Skip to main content

Full text of "The meaning of truth in history"

See other formats


.9 


UC-NRLF 


O 

03 
00 

OJ 
'CD 


Btubemtp  of 


CREIGHTON    LECTURE 


THE     MEANING    OF 
TRUTH     IN    HISTORY 

BY   THE 

RIGHT  HON.  VISCOUNT  HALDANE 

K.T.,    F.R.S. 
(Lord  High  Chancellor  of  Great  Britain) 


BEING    THE    CREIGHTON    LECTURE    FOR    THE 

YEAR    1913-14,    DELIVERED    BEFORE    THE 

UNIVERSITY   ON    MARCH  6th,  1914 


iUmlron: 


of  Eonimn 


PUBLISHED    FOR    THE    UNIVERSITY    OF    LONDON    PRESS,    LTD. 
BY  HODDER  &  STOUGHTON,   WARWICK  SQUARE,    LONDON,   E.G. 


THE    MEANING    OF 
TRUTH    IN    HISTORY 


Stmbmttg  of  ILontrott 


CREIGHTON    LECTURE 


THE     MEANING    OF 
TRUTH    IN    HISTORY 

BY  THE 

RIGHT  HON.  VISCOUNT  HALDANE 

K.T..    F.R.S. 
(Lord  High  Chancellor  of  Great  Britain) 


BEING    THE    CREIGHTON    LECTURE    FOR    THE 

YEAR   1913-14,    DELIVERED    BEFORE    THE 

UNIVERSITY  ON   MARCH  6th,  1914 


iUmlron:   SJnibemtg  of  JUmfcott 

JBLISHED    FOR    THE    UNIVERSITY    OF    LONDON    PRESS,    LTD. 
BY  HODDER  &  STOUGHTON,   WARWICK  SQUARE,   LONDON,   E.G. 

1914 


. 


THE  MEANING  OF  TRUTH 
IN   HISTORY. 


The  occasion  on  which  it  is  my  privilege  to 
iddress  you  is  one  which  is  associated  with  the  name 
>f  a  remarkable  man.  He  possessed  gifts  of  intel- 
lect and  of  character  which  would  have  made  him 
eminent  in  careers  other  than  the  one  he  chose  for 
himself.  But  he  held  tenaciously  the  principle, 
adherence  to  which  is  essential  for  a  man  who 
genuinely  aspires  to  accomplish  anything  lasting. 
He  knew  that  he  must  concentrate,  and  he  did  so. 
He  lived  a  dedicated  life — dedicated  to  the  service 
of  his  God  and  his  Church,  as  he  conceived  them. 
Such  were  his  gifts  that  his  work  deeply  impressed 
with  the  sense  of  its  reality  those  who  were  permitted 
to  come  near  him.  The  impression  he  made  was 
heightened  by  his  obvious  conviction  that  he  could 
best  render  the  service  to  which  he  had  consecrated 
his  life  by  following  truth  unswervingly,  and  seeking 


as  well  a'S  ke:  could  to  extend  the  province  of  genuine 
knowledge.  The  result  of  an  unfaltering  adhesion 
to  this  principle  was  that  his  writings  produced  on 
the  public  an  impression  of  sincerity  and  thorough- 
ness, an  impression  which  deepened  as  time  went  on. 
In  so  far  as  he  devoted  his  gifts  to  the  study  of 
history,  it  was  therefore  natural  that  his  integrity  of 
purpose  and  his  desire  for  the  truth  should  lead  to 
his  becoming  known  and  trusted  as  an  historian  of 
a  wide  and  searching  outlook. 

It  accords  with  what  is  fitting  that  among  the 
memorials  erected  to  him  there  should  have  been 
included  this  lectureship.  To  me  it  has  fallen  to  be 
the  lecturer  this  year,  and  to  choose  a  topic  that  is 
appropriate.  What  Bishop  Creighton  cared  for  in 
historical  work  was,  above  all,  to  treat  the  facts 
justly,  to  see  things  not  merely  on  the  side  that  is 
external  and  superficial  and  therefore  transitory, 
but  in  their  fuller  and  more  enduring  significance. 
It  is  out  of  a  feeling  of  respect  for  this  characteristic 
of  his  life  and  writing  that  I  have  selected  for  my 
subject  "The  Meaning  of  Truth  in  History." 

But  the  subject  is  full  of  difficulty.  As  decade 
succeeds  decade,  we  in  this  country  are  learning 
more  and  more,  in  science,  in  art,  and  in  religion 
alike,  that  the  question, "  What  is  Truth  ?  "  is  a  ques- 
tion of  far-reaching  significance,  a  significance  that 
seems  to  reach  farther  the  more  we  reflect.  And 
the  perplexity  of  the  question  extends  not  least  to 
the  case  of  the  historian.  For  it  seems  to-day  that  • 


the  genuine  historian  must  be  more  than  a  biographer 
or  a  recorder.  The  field  of  his  enquiry  cannot  be 
limited  by  the  personality  of  any  single  human 
being,  nor  can  it  be  occupied  by  any  mere  enumera- 
tion of  details  or  chronicle  of  events.  A  great  man, 
such  as  Caesar  or  Charlemagne,  may  stand  for  a 
period,  but  his  personality  is,  after  all,  a  feature 
that  is  transitory.  The  §£intjxL^he_ageis  generally 
greater  and  more  lasting  than  the  spirit  of  any 
individual.  The  spirit  of  the  age  is  also  more  than 
a  mere  aggregate  of  the  events  that  a  period  can 
display,  or  than  any  mere  sum  of  individual  wills. 
What,  then,  is  to  be  the  standard  of  truth  for  the 
historian?  The  analogy  of  the  artist  who  paints  a 
portrait  may  prove  not  without  significance  for  the 
answer  to  this  question.  The  great  artist  does  not 
put  on  canvas  a  simple  reproduction  of  the  appear- 
ance of  his  subject  at  a  particular  moment;  that  is 
the  work  of  the  photographer.  Art,  in  the  highest 
sense,  has  to  disentangle  the  significance  of  the 
whole  from  its  details  and  to  reproduce  it.  The 
truth  of  art  is  a  truth  that  must  thus  be  born  again 
of  the  artist's  mind.  No  mere  narration  of  details 
will  give  the  whole  that  at  once  dominates  these 
details  and  yet  does  not  exist  apart  from  them. 
But  art,  with  its  freedom  to  choose  and  to  reject, 
selects  details  and  moulds  them  into  a  shape  that 
is  symbolic  of  what  is  at  once  ideal  and  real.  In 
art,  thought  and  sense  enter  into  the  closest  union, 
or  rather  they  form  an  entirety  within  which  both 


are  abstractions  from  an  actual  that  does  not  let 
itself  be  broken  up. 

Now  the  historian  surely  must  resemble  the 
portrait  painter  rather  than  the  photographer.  The 
secret  of  the  art  of  a  Gibbon  or  a  Mommsen  seems 
to  lie  in  this :  that  they  select  their  details,  select 
those  that  are  relevant  and  that  can  be  moulded 
into  a  characteristic  setting  without  sacrifice  of 
integrity  or  accuracy,  a  setting  which  is  typical  of 
a  period.  At  some  point  or  other  we  may  want  to 
have  the  details  which  have  been  passed  by.  We 
may  want  them  for  a  picture  of  the  period  under 
another  aspect.  But  we  do  not  always  want  all  the 
details.  "  Le  secret  d'ennuyer  c'est  tout  dire." 
Carlyle  passed  much  by  when  he  wrote  his  French 
Revolution,  and  it  is  well  that  he  did.  We  find 
what  he  left  alone  in  other  historians  who  present 
the  story  from  a  different  standpoint.  Just  as  there 
may  be  several  portraits,  all  of  superlative  excel- 
lence, while  differing  in  details  and  even  in  their 
presentation  of  actual  features,  so  there  may  be 
several  histories,  equal  in  value,  but  differing  in  a 
similar  fashion. 

To  judge,  then,  of  excellence  in  the  historian  we 
must  possess  a  standard  not  wrholly  dissimilar  from 
that  by  which  we  judge  of  excellence  in  the  artist. 
In  the  case  of  the  artist,  there  can  be  little  doubt 
about  one  point,  at  all  events,  in  that  standard. 
Whether  it  is  nature  or  man  that  he  presents,  the 
image  must  interpret  character.  It  does  not  detract 


9 

from  the  truth  of  the  work  of  the  artist  that  the 
cottage  and  the  figures  in  his  landscape  never 
existed  exactly  as  he  has  painted  them,  or  even  at 
.all.  What  is  important  is  that  they  should  suggest 
the  deeper  and  more  enduring  meaning  of  what  is 
actual,  in  the  fullest  and  most  important  sense. 
The  expression  which  the  portrait  painter  has  put 
on  canvas  may  be  a  rare  one — the  expression, 
perhaps  of  an  individuality  seized  at  a  unique 
moment  of  existence.  But  all  the  more  does  that 
expression  stand  out  as  the  truth  about  the  real 
life  of  the  man  whose  portrait  is  there.  Now,  the 
historian  also  is  concerned  with  what  is  ideal.  He 
is  concerned  with  this  just  because  it  is  only  through 
the  ideal  that  what  has  happened  can  be  lifted  above 
the  particularity  of  the  events  that  obscure  its 
meaning.  M.  Renan  has  put  this  point  admir- 
ably :— 

"II  n'y  a  guere  de  details  certains  en  histoire; 
les  details  cependant  ont  toujours  quelque  signi- 
fication. Le  talent  de  1'historien  consiste  a  faire  un 
ensemble  vrai  avec  des  traits  qui  ne  sont  vrai  qu'a 
demi."  And  again  : — "  L'histoire  pure  doit  con- 
struire  son  edifice  avec  deux  sortes  de  donnees,  et, 
si  j'ose  le  dire,  deux  facteurs;  d'abord,  Petat 
general  de  Tame  humaine  en  un  siecle  et  dans  un 
pays  donnes;  en  second  lieu,  les  incidents  par- 
ticuliers  qui,  se  combinant  avec  les  causes  generates, 
ont  determine  le  cours  des  evenements.  Expliquer 
1'histoire  par  des  incidents  est  aussi  faux  que  de 


10 

1'expliquer    par     des    principes    purement    philo- 
^sophiques.       Les    deux    explications     doivent    se 
soutenir  et  se  completer  Tune  1'autre."1 

The  work  of  the  historian  and  that  of  the  artist 
seem  to  be  so  far  analogous.  Both  are  directed  to 
finding  the  true  expression  of  their  subjects. 
Neither  is  concerned  with  accidents  of  detail  that 
are  fortuitous.  But  the  analogy  extends  only  a 
little  way,  for  the  subjects  are  very  different.  That 
of  a  portrait  is,  after  all,  a  single  and  isolated  per- 
sonality. It  is  the  business  of  the  artist  to  express 
this  personality,  and  to  express  it  as  a  work  of  art 
in  which  thought  and  feeling  are  blended  in  a  unity 
that  cannot  be  broken  up.  But  the  historian  is  not 
concerned  with  any  single  personality.  His  work 
seems  rather  to  be  to  display  the  development  of  a 
nation  or  of  a  period,  and  to  record  accurately,  and 
in  the  light  of  the  spirit  of  the  nation  or  period, 
the  sequence  of  events  in  which  its  character  has 
manifested  itself.  Like  the  artist,  the  historian 
may  omit  many  details.  But  he  does  not  possess 
the  freedom  of  the  artist.  What  we  ask  from  the 
great  painter  is  his  interpretation  of  a  personality, 
and  he  may  take  liberties  in  imagining  costume  and 
background.  Indeed,  he  often  must  take  liberties, 
for  the  expression  counts  for  more  than  circum- 
stances which  obscure  rather  than  assist  in  revealing 
it.  But  the  picture  created  by  the  historian,  though 
it,  too,  can  only  be  created  by  his  genius  and  must 

1  { Vie  de  Jesus',  Preface  de  la  treizieme  Edition. 


II 

be  born  of  his  mind,  is  of  a  different  order.  The 
presentation  of  the  whole  and  the  description  of 
actual  facts  are  here  more  closely  related.  Literal 
accuracy  counts  for  much,  for  others  than  himself 
will  claim  the  liberty  to  refer  to  his  book  for  actual 
facts,  and  to  interpret  them,  it  may  be,  differently 
from  his  rendering.  Thus  the  historian  is  under 
restrictions  greater  than  those  of  the  artist.  If  he 
uses  as  complete  a  liberty  as  the  artist  claims,  he 
is  reckoned  as  belonging  to  quite  a  different  pro- 
fession, that  of  a  writer  of  historical  romance,  such 
as  the  romances  of  Sir  Walter  Scott. 

But  this  is  not  all.  The  artist  depicts  as  what  is 
characteristic  an  expression  that  may  have  been 
found  only  at  one  moment  in  the  history  of  his 
subject.  The  historian  has  to  present  events  and 
their  meaning  over  a  period  that  is  often  long. 
Even  occurrences  that  seem  isolated,  like  the  execu- 
tion of  Charles  I.,  or  the  taking  of  the  Bastille,  or 
the  Battle  of  Waterloo,  have  to  be  shown  as  cul- 
minating events  in  a  course  of  development  which 
must  be  recorded  because  apart  from  it  they  lose 
their  significance.  It  is  only  by  tracing  the  genesis 
not  merely  of  culminating  events  but  of  national 
institutions,  and  by  exhibiting  them  as  the  outcome 
and  embodiment  of  the  genius  of  the  people  to 
whom  they  belong,  that  in  many  cases  they  can  be 
made  intelligible.  This  principle  is  the  foundation 
of  the  historical  method.  It  is  a  principle  which 
to-day  seems  almost  a  commonplace,  but  it  has  not 


12 

always  been  so.  It  is  striking  to  observe  how  really 
great  writers  suffer  when  they  violate  it.  Some 
extreme  instances  are  to  be  found  among  the  his- 
torians of  Jurisprudence.  I  will  take  two  cases  of 
the  kind,  and  I  offer  no  apology  for  turning  aside 
for  a  moment  to  the  highly  specialised  branch  of 
history  from  which  I  take  them.  For  they  are 
admirable  examples  of  the  fault  in  method  which  I 
wish  to  illustrate.  Moreover,  I  am  a  lawyer  whose 
almost  daily  duty  it  is  to  ascertain  the  reasons  why 
the  law  has  become  what  it  is,  because  unless  I  can 
do  so,  I  am  bound  to  fail  in  the  interpretation  of 
its  scope  and  authority.  There  has  thus  been  forced 
on  me  direct  experience  of  the  embarrassment  which 
the  fault  of  which  I  am  speaking  causes.  Those 
who  have  to  consult  almost  daily  otherwise  great 
books  dealing  with  the  history  of  legal  institutions 
encounter  this  fault  in  its  worst  form. 

I  will  refer  first  to  the  shortcomings  of  a  really 
remarkable  Englishman.  The  case  of  Jeremy 
Bentham  is  notable.  He  ignored  the  light  which 
history  had  to  throw  on  the  institutions  about  which 
he  was  writing,  and  his  reputation  thereby  suffered. 
He  rendered  great  services  to  the  cause  of  law 
reform  in  England  and  elsewhere  by  the  force  of 
his  destructive  criticism.  The  very  abstractness  of 
his  methods  added  to  the  incisiveness  of  this 
criticism.  But  when  he  describes,  and  even  where 
he  brings  an  indictment  that  is  obviously  true,  he 
is,  generally  speaking,  utterly  defective  as  an  his- 


13 

torian.  His  unconsciousness  of  the  genesis  of  the 
facts  with  which  he  is  dealing  is  extraordinary  in 
a  man  of  such  acuteness.  He  attributes  the  con- 
tinued existence  of  bad  laws  to  the  unscrupulous- 
ness  of  contemporary  rulers  and  judges,  as  if  they 
had  individually  devised  them.  When,  for  example, 
with  admirable  insistence,  he  denounces  the  exist- 
ence of  the  rule  which,  contrary  to  what  we  now 
regard  as  plain  common-sense,  used  to  prevent  a 
party  to  a  suit  from  giving  evidence  in  it,  he  is 
apparently  unconscious  of  the  fact  that  there  was 
once  a  stage  in  the  evolution  of  public  opinion  at 
which  it  was  inevitable  that  the  rule  should  be  what 
it  was.1  While  religious  opinion  dominated  in 
matters  secular,  it  was  almost  universally  held  that 
to  allow  an  interested  party  to  give  evidence  on  his 
own  behalf  was  to  tempt  him  to  perjury,  and  perjury, 
which  meant  everlasting  damnation,  seemed  to  our 
forefathers  a  more  disastrous  result  than  the  loss 
of  property.  It  was,  in  such  a  period,  quite  natural 
that  public  opinion  should  prefer  spiritual  safety  to 
secular  justice,  and  fashion  law  accordingly.  We 
have  to  understand  that  this  was  so,  if  we  would 
understand  the  history  of  the  rules  which  restricted 
the  admission  of  evidence  in  the  Courts  of  England. 
That  we  have  now  passed  to  a  different  standpoint 
does  not  lessen  the  necessity.  Bentham  again,  to 

i  See  his  remarks  on  Blackstone  and  the  Judges  in  his 
'Rationale  of  Judicial  Evidence,'  Book  IX,  C.  5  (Vol.  7  of 
Bowring's  Edition  of  his  Works.) 


take  another  example,  denounced  the  Roman  law 
as  being  a  parcel  of  dissertations  badly  drawn  up  ! 
He  knew  nothing  of  its  history  or  of  the  circum- 
stances of  its  development.  He  had  not  heard  of 
the  work  of  the  great  historical  school  of  Roman 
law  which  Savigny  was  even  then  leading.  His 
method  was  always  to  assume  certain  abstract  prin- 
ciples, and  to  judge  everything  in  their  light  without 
regard  to  time  or  place.  He  insisted  on  immediate 
codification,  just  as  Savigny,  on  the  other  hand, 
insisted  on  the  postponement  of  codes  until  the 
common  law  had  completed  a  full  course  of  natural 
growth.  But  Savigny  himself,  to  take  my  second 
illustration,  at  times  incurred  the  perils  which  are 
inseparable  from  occasional  lapses  into  abstract- 
ness  of  mind.  Although  he  was  an  apostle  of  the 
historical  method,  and,  in  general,  took  far  more 
account  of  history  than  did  Bentham,  he,  too,  at 
moments,  made  what  to  a  later  generation  have 
become  mistakes.  For  example,  he  attacked  the 
code  which  Napoleon  had  enacted  for  France.  He 
attacked  it  on  the  ground  that  to  enact  such  a  code 
was  unscientific.1  He  was  probably  right  in  desir- 
ing that  the  spirit  of  the  great  Roman  lawyers 
should  continue,  at  least  for  a  time,  to  work  through- 
out Germany,  where  it  held  sway,  unobstructed  by 
the  rules  of  a  rigid  code.  In  that  country,  where 

1  See  the  section  headed  '  Die  drei  neuen  Gesetzbiicher,'  in  his 
book  'Vom  Beruf  unsrer  Zeit  fur  Gesetzgebung  und  Rechts 
wissenschaft.' 


the  tradition  of  the  Roman  law  actually  occupied 
the  field,  the  provisions  of  a  code  might  well  have 
proved  not  only  unduly  rigid,  but  also  artificial. 
Yet  his  attack  on  Napoleon's  great  Code  did  not  do 
justice  to  the  overwhelming  reasons  for  enacting  it 
in  France.  France,  unlike  Germany,  had,  before 
Napoleon's  time,  no  general  body  of  laws.  The 
different  parts  of  the  country  were  subject  to  utterly 
divergent  systems,  such  as  were  the  Customs  of 
Paris  and  of  Normandy.  It  was  remarked  by 
Voltaire  that  a  man  travelling  in  France  in  his  own 
time  changed  laws  as  often  as  he  changed  horses. 
The  rough  common-sense  of  Napoleon  saw  that  a 
general  code  was  a  necessity.  He  framed  one  that 
was  not  ideal,  judged  by  the  high  standards  of 
Savigny,  but  it  was  the  best  he  could  frame  at  a 
time  when  nothing  was  to  be  hoped  for  in  the  way 
of  development  on  the  basis  of  the  prevailing  laws. 
Gradual  reform  of  this  kind  might  well  have  been 
possible  had  the  Roman  law  been  the  general 
foundation  of  a  single  system  of  jurisprudence  in 
France.  But  it  was  not  so,  and  Napoleon  therefore 
took  the  course  which  the  necessities  of  the  time 
dictated. 

I  have  cited  these  examples  of  the  desirability  of 
the  historical  spirit  in  estimating  legal  institutions, 
partly  because  they  illustrate  admirably  the  truth 
of  the  saying  of  Balduinus,  a  great  jurist  of  the 
sixteenth  century,  "  Sine  historia  caecam  esse  juris- 
prudentiam."  But  I  have  cited  them  also  because 


i6 

they  illustrate  the  wider  proposition  that  no  event 
in  history  of  any  kind  can  be  judged  without  full 
knowledge  of  its  context  and  of  the  spirit  of  its 
particular  age.  The  execution  of  Charles  L 
has  been  the  subject  of  the  hottest  controversy. 
Did  the  tribunal  which  decreed  it  sit  wholly  without 
constitutional  warrant,  and  was  the  trial  conducted 
quite  illegally?  Probably  both  questions  must  be 
answered  affirmatively  from  the  standpoint  of  the 
common  law.  But  this  does  not  conclude  the  discus- 
sion. It  is  true  that  acts  of  the  kind — that  is,  revolu- 
tionary acts — are  outside  the  provisions  of  ordinary 
law.  And  yet  they  may  be  justified  under  what  is 
called  martial  law,  but  is,  in  our  country,  only  an 
application  of  the  maxim,  "  Salus  populi  suprema 
lex."  Had  Cromwell  not  put  Charles  to  death,  it 
was  more  than  merely  possible  that  Charles  would 
have  seized  the  first  chance  of  putting  Cromwell 
himself  to  death  and  of  upsetting  the  new  order  of 
government.  As  Lord  Morley,  in  his  "  Life  of 
Cromwell,"  has  pointed  out,  the  real  justification  of 
Cromwell  must  depend  on  the  question  whether 
what  can  only  be  justified  as  an  act  of  war,  was  or 
was  not  a  public  necessity.  And  the  answer  to  this 
question  requires  that  the  problem  should  be  ap- 
proached as  a  large  one,  and  in  the  spirit  which 
demands  a  survey  of  the  events  of  the  periods  both 
before  and  after  the  year  1649.  The  judgment  of 
posterity  upon  the  act  of  Oliver  Cromwell  must 
turn,  not  on  what  he  was  as  an  individual,  but  on 


: 

+< 


: 


; 


the  extent  to  which  he  was  the  representative  figure 
in  a  movement  which  must  be  judged  before  he 
can  be  approved  or  condemned. 

Now  it  is  just  this  obligation  of  the  historian  that 
makes  his  work  so  difficult.  Like  the  portrait  painter, 
he  has,  in  his  search  after  expression,  to  select 
details,  but  he  has  to  select  them  under  far  more 
stringent  conditions  as  to  completeness  and  accuracy. 
Exact  these  details  must  be,  but  complete  they  can- 

ot  be.  Much  must  be  rejected  as  irrelevant.  The 
test  of  relevancy  is  the  standard  of  what  is  neces- 
sary, not  merely  for  exactness,  but  for  the  adequate 
portraiture  of  the  spirit  of  the  time.  And  this  test 
necessitates  great  insight  into  the  characteristics  of 
that  spirit.  Otherwise  misleading  details  will  be 
selected,  and  undue  prominences  and  proportions 
will  be  assigned.  The  historian  must  be  able  to 
estimate  what  are  the  true  and  large  characteristics 
of  the  age,  and  one  test  of  his  success  will  be,  as 
in  the  case  of  the  artist,  the  test  of  his  stature.  Can 

e  rise  high  enough  to  present  the  truth  in  what, 
almost  as  it  were  by  direct  perception,  we  seem  to 
recognise  as  a  great  form  of  deep  significance?  I 
say  almost  by  direct  perception,  for  the  analogy  of 

e  intuition  of  art  and  literature  appears  to  come 
in  here.  One  recognises  the  quality  of  size  in  a 
Gibbon  or  a  Carlyle,  as  one  recognises  it  in  the 
great  portrait  painter  and  the  great  dramatic  poet. 
But  in  the  domain  of  history  the  predominance  of 
this  quality  is  conditioned  by  the  imperative  duty  to 


14360 


i8 

be  accurate  to  an  extent  that  is  incumbent  neither 
on  the  painter  nor  on  the  poet.  The  historian  who 
has  a  whole  period  to  describe  must  be  more  than 
exact;  he  has  to  be  lord  over  his  details.  He  must 
marshal  these  details  and  tower  above  them,  and 
reject  and  select  in  the  light  of  nothing  less  than 
the  whole.  He  must  not  let  his  view  of  that  whole, 
as  has  been  the  case  with  both  a  Bossuet,  on  the 
one  hand,  and  a  Buckle,  on  the  other,  be  distorted 
by  a  priori  conceptions  that  are  abstract  and  in- 
adequate to  the  riches  of  the  facts  of  life.  He  must 
frame  his  estimate  after  a  study  of  the  whole 
sequence  of  events,  of  those  events  which  throw 
light  on  the  conduct  and  characteristics  of  a  nation 
in  the  variety  of  phases  in  its  existence.  It  is  just 
here  that  he  is  apt  to  be  beset  by  obsessions  that 
come  from  unconscious  pre-judgments. 

I  wish  to  try  to  say  something  about  the  origin 
of  this  kind  of  temptation  to  pre-judgment — a 
temptation  to  which  a  long  list  of  historians  have 
succumbed  in  a  greater  or  less  degree.  Indeed,  no 
one  can  wholly  escape  it.  But  it  has  various  forms, 
some  of  which  are  worse  than  others.  In  those  that 
are  most  misleading  it  seems  to  arise  from  an  in- 
sufficiently considered  application  of  the  conceptions 
under  which  the  observer  searches  after  facts,  con- 
ceptions which  are  often  too  narrow  for  the  facts 
themselves.  It  appears  as  exactly  the  same  kind  of 
temptation  as  that  into  which  in  various  forms 
students  of  the  exact  sciences  have  been  prone  to 


19 

fall.  I  will  therefore  ask  you  to  bear  with  me  while 
I  touch  on  the  general  subject  of  scientific  method. 
For  in  every  department  of  science  just  the  same 
difficulty  arises  as  arises  in  that  of  the  historian,  and 
the  source  of  these  difficulties  in  some  branches  of 
science  can  be  easily  traced.  Facts  are  apt  to  be 
distorted  in  the  mind  of  the  observer  by  pre- 
conceived hypotheses  of  which  he  is  hardly  con- 
scious. The  attempts  which  have  been  made  to 
exhibit  the  life  of  an  organism  as  the  result  of 
physical  forces  operating  from  without  on  an  aggre- 
gate of  minute  mechanisms  or  chemical  compounds, 
have,  notwithstanding  their  usefulness  from  the 
point  of  view  of  physics  and  chemistry,  fallen  short 
as  regards  the  nature  of  life  itself.  When  we  are 
confronted  with  the  unquestionable  facts  of  repro- 
duction and  heredity,  these  attempts  have  always 
broken  down.  We  are  driven  to  admit,  not  the  exist- 
ence of  a  special  vital  force  controlling  development 
from  without,  but  the  conception  of  something  in 
the  nature  of  an  end  realising  itself,  a  whole  which 
exists  only  in  what  it  controls,  but  which,  while  it 
may  still  fall  far  short  of  conscious  purpose,  is  not 
on  that  account  less  real.  We  may,  indeed,  dislike 
expressions  which  suggest  abstract  or  even  conscious 
purpose,  and  prefer,  with  the  author  of  that  remark- 
able book,  "  Creative  Evolution,"  to  speak  of  what 
is  realised  as  a  tendency  rather  than  an  end.  But 
one  thing  is  clear,  however  we  may  express  our- 
selves. We  must  not  let  the  terror  of  theology  and 

14360  B  2 


2O 

the  supernatural,  which  often  afflicts  men  of  science 
with  fears,  deflect  us  from  our  duty  to  be  true  in  our 
descriptions  to  actual  experience,  and  drive  us  by 
way  of  reaction  into  purely  mechanistic  theories 
which  are  inadequate  to  explain  it.  The  history  of 
biology  seems  to  have  been  at  times  as  sad  an  illus- 
tration of  the  dangers  of  anti-theological  dogmas  as 
it  has  at  other  periods  been  of  the  dangers  of  those 
of  a  theological  teleology. 

In  the  same  way,  if  we  would  know  the  truth 
about  men  and  affairs,  we  must  learn  to  study  their 
history  quite  simply  and  with  minds  as  free  as  we 
can  make  them  from  prejudice.  Our  preconcep- 
tions generally  arise  from  our  having  unconsciously 
become  metaphysicians.  We  do  not  need  to  be 
metaphysicians  at  all,  except  to  the  modest  extent 
of  knowing  how  to  guard  against  falling  without 
being  aware  of  it  into  bad  metaphysics.  Uncon- 
scious prejudice  is  apt  to  tempt  us  to  deny  the  reality 
of  much  of  the  world  as  it  seems,  and  seek  to  stretch 
that  world  on  the  rack  of  some  special  principle  of 
very  limited  application.  The  only  way  of  safety 
is  to  train  the  mind  to  be  on  the  watch  for  the 
intrusion  of  limited  and  exclusive  ideas.  If  to  yield 
to  such  intrusion  is  dangerous  in  the  field  of  biology, 
the  danger  becomes  still  more  apparent  when  we 
are  confronted  with  the  phenomena  which  belong 
to  the  region  of  human  existence.  We  can  neither 
deny  the  reality  of  the  moral  and  intellectual  atmo- 
sphere in  which,  as  persons,  we  live  and  move  and 


21 


have  our  being,  nor  resolve  it  into  the  constructions 
which  represent  the  utmost  limits  attainable  by  the 
mathematical  and  physical  sciences.  Of  all  that 
really  lives,  Goethe's  well-known  criticism  appears 
to  be  true  : — 


"Wer  will  was  Lebendig's  erkennen  und  beschreiben 
Sucht  erst  den  Geist  heraus  zu  treiben, 
Dan  hat  er  die  Theile  in  seiner  Hand, 
Fehlt  leider  nur  das  geistige  Band." 


I  In  point  of  fact,  the  warning  which  Goethe  gave 
to  the  biologist  of  his  time  is  not  less  important  for 
the  student  of  history.  The  latter,  also,  must  refuse 

•  the  injunctions  to  limit  his  outlook  which  come  from 
the  materialist,  and  he  must  refuse  not  less  sternly 
the  counter-materialism  of  those  who  would  seek  in 
the  events  of  the  world  only  for  the  interference 
and  mechanical  guidance  of  a  Power  operating  from 
without.  He  must  recognise,  too,  the  reality  of 
social  wholes,  outside  of  which  individuals  cannot 
live — social  wholes  which  are  actual  just  in  so  far  as 
the  individuals  who  compose  them  in  some  measure 
think  and  will  identically.  For,  apart  from  his 
social  surroundings,  the  individual  appears  to  have 
no  adequate  life.  Such  social  wholes  cannot  be 
satisfactorily  described  in  biological  language.  The 
practice  of  attempting  to  so  express  them  is  a  very 
common  one.  People  talk  of  social  organisms  and 
their  development  by  means  of  natural  selection. 
But  in  speaking  of  the  organisation  of  society  and 
of  its  development,  we  have  passed  into  a  region 


22 

where  the  categories  of  biology  are  not  adequate. 
In  this  region  we  only  darken  counsel  by  using 
phrases  drawn  from  the  vocabulary  of  a  branch  of 
knowledge  that  does  not  take  account  of  conscious 
purpose  and  of  the  intelligence  and  volition  which 
are  characteristic  of  persons  as  distinguished  from 
organisms.  No  doubt  human  beings  are  organisms. 
But  they  are  also  much  more  than  organisms.  The 
biological  method  in  history  and  sociology  is  there- 
fore unsatisfactory.  It  may  be,  and  sometimes 
must  be  used,  just  as  are  the  methods  of  physics 
and  chemistry  in  biology  itself.  But  its  application 
ought  always  to  be  a  restricted  and  guarded  one, 
because,  if  the  application  is  made  uncritically,  the 
reality  of  much  that  is  actual  in  present  and  past 
alike  will  inevitably  be  ignored.  Darwinian  methods 
and  conceptions  avail  here  only  to  a  very  limited 
extent.  For  the  social  wholes  with  which  history  has 
to  deal  are  conscious  wholes  representing  intelli- 
gence and  volition. 

And  this  is  why  the  historian  is  not  only  at  liberty, 
but  is  bound  to  recognise  in  the  spirit  of  an  age 
something  of  which  he  can  legitimately  take  account. 
It  is  also  the  reason  why  he  can  never  be  a  mere 
recorder,  and  why  he  must  always  be  a  man  of  Art 
as  well  as  of  Science.  For  Art  alone  can  adequately 
make  the  idea  of  the  whole  shine  forth  in  the  par- 
ticulars in  which  it  is  immanent,  and  this  is  as  true 
of  the  history  of  a  period  as  it  is  of  a  moment  in 
the  life  of  a  man. 


23 

In  saying  these  things,  I  am  far  from  suggesting 
that  the  historian  should  become  a  student  of  philo- 
sophy with  a  view  to  having  a  standpoint  of  his 
own.  I  have  touched  on  the  topic  for  a  directly 
contrary  purpose.  I  am  anxious  that  he  should  not 
unconsciously  commit  the  fault  of  a  Bossuet  or  a 
Bentham  or  a  Buckle  by  slipping  into  a  philo- 
sophical attitude  without  knowing  it.  It  may  well 
be  that  he  cannot  avoid  placing  himself  at  some 
particular  standpoint  for  the  purposes  of  his  review. 
Most  historians  seem  to  me  to  do  so  to  a  greater  or 
less  degree.  What  I  am  concerned  about  is  simply 
to  make  it  plain  that  the  choice  of  such  a  standpoint 
is  no  easy  matter,  or  one  that  a  man  dare  lightly 
adventure.  And  I  have  said  what  I  have,  simply 
for  the  purpose  of  laying  emphasis  on  the  need,  in 
making  such  a  choice,  of  knowledge  of  the  alterna- 
tives and  consciousness  of  the  magnitude  of  the 
field  of  controversy.  The  historian  has  to  approach 
the  records  of  the  experience  of  nations  with  a  mind 
sufficiently  open  to  enable  him  to  attach  weight  to 
every  phase  of  that  experience.  His  conception  of 
it  must  be  sufficiently  wide  to  enable  him  to  take 
account  of  every  aspect  which  he  may  encounter. 
He  must  exclude  neither  rationality  nor  irrationality. 
Now,  if  experience  thus  conceived  be  the  material 
on  which  the  historian  has  to  operate,  his  method 
must  not  be  either  to  search  for  and  record  isolated 
facts  which  can  never  really  be  interpreted  apart 
from  their  context,  or  to  set  out  abstract  principles. 


24 

The  very  width  of  his  field  of  research  must  neces- 
sitate the  selection  of  his  facts  and  their  relation  to 
each  other  and  to  the  particular  system  in  which 
'alone  they  have  their  meaning.  For  meaning  is  the 
foundation  of  system  in  history.  The  sense  of  this, 
and  the  extraordinary  difficulty  which  the  historian 
has  in  determining  what  is  relevant  and  what  is  not 
relevant  to  a  true  interpretation,  has  caused  some 
critics  to  despair  of  history,  and  others  to  try  to 
confine  its  task  in  a  fashion  which,  if  strictly  carried 
out,  would  deprive  the  historian  of  the  chance  of 
calling  to  his  aid  the  method  of  the  artist.  It  is 
interesting  to  observe  to  what  lengths  these  two 
divergent  tendencies  have  been  carried. 

I  will  refer  first  to  the  criticism  which  rejects  the 
possibility  of  reliable  history  altogether.  In  his 
"  Farbenlehre,"  Goethe  makes  an  observation  on 
the  value  of  exact  records.  "  We  are  told,"  he  says, 
"  to  look  to  the  spirit  rather  than  to  the  letter. 
Usually,  however,  the  spirit  has  destroyed  the  letter, 
or  has  so  altered  it  that  nothing  remains  of  its 
original  character  and  significance."  He  puts  the 
same  thought  in  another  fashion  when  he  makes 
Faust  say  to  Wagner,  in  an  often-quoted  passage  : — 

"  Mein  Freund,  die  Zeiten  der  Vergangenheit, 
Sind  uns  ein  Buch  mit  sieben  Siegeln  ; 
Was  ihr  den  Geist  der  Zeiten  heisst, 
Das  ist  im  Grund  der  Herren  eigner  Geist 
In  dem  die  Zeiten  sich  bespiegeln." 

This  seems  a  highly  sceptical  utterance.  The 
historian  is  told  that  he  can  succeed  neither  in 


25 

recovering  the  spirit  of  the  past,  nor  in  discovering 
its  letter.  And  if  the  historian  were  faced  with  the 
dilemma  Goethe  puts  to  him,  his  case  would  indeed 
be  a  difficult  one.  But  is  it  so  ?  Let  us  look  at  the 
case  of  records.  Goethe  was  no  doubt  right  in  his 
scepticism  about  mere  records.  For  if  a  man  in- 
dulges himself  with  the  belief  that  in  quoting 
records  accurately  he  is  collecting  the  truth  about 
the  history  of  a  period,  he  is  indulging  himself 
rashly.  What  do  such  records  consist  of?  Bio-  / 
graphics  written  at  the  time,  letters,  and  State 
papers  are  their  main  forms.  As  to  the  biographies, 
they  are  often  valuable  as  presenting  a  fine  portrait 
of  their  subject;  and  the  narrative  and  the  corre- 
spondence quoted  are,  of  course,  of  much  use.  But 
they  are  almost  invariably  coloured.  The  selection 
of  material  is  necessarily  dependent  on  the  object 
with  which  the  selection  is  made,  and  that  is  the 
biography  of  one  man.  You  have  only  to  read 
another  biography,  that  of  his  political  rival,  in 
order,  if  they  were  both  famous  men,  to  realise  that 
whatever  value  the  story  possesses  as  portraiture,  it 
is  by  no  means  to  be  relied  on  implicitly  for  a 
scientific  record  of  the  facts.  Lord  Morley,  in  his 
"  Notes  on  Politics  and  History,"  quotes  Bismarck 
on  this  point.  Reading  a  book  of  superior  calibre, 
that  remarkable  man  once  came,  so  Lord  Morley 
tells  us,  on  a  portrait  of  an  eminent  personage  whom 
he  had  known  well.  "  Such  a  man  as  is  described 
here,"  he  cried,  "  never  existed.  It  is  not  in  diplo- 


26 

matic  materials,  but  in  their  life  of  every  day  that 
you  come  to  know  men."  So,  remarks  Lord  Morley, 
does  a  singularly  good  judge  warn  us  of  the  perils 
of  archivial  research. 

As  to  isolated  letters,  there  again  colour  is  inevit- 
ably present.  The  writers,  however  intimately 
acquainted  with  the  facts,  are  too  near  to  see  them  in 
their  proper  perspective.  From  their  correspond- 
ence many  fragments  of  solid  and  useful  fact  may 
be  extracted ;  but  the  bulk  of  what  is  there  is,  taken 
by  itself,  unreliable  material  for  the  historian.  It 
is  only  by  careful  selection  from  a  variety  of  sources, 
and  by  recasting — that  is,  by  following  the  method 
of  Art  rather  than  that  of  Science — that  he  can  pro- 
duce the  true  expression  of  the  period  as  a  living 
whole. 

State  papers,  again,  are  written  by  Ministers,  or 
by  diplomatists,  or,  more  often,  by  their  officials 
under  somewhat  loose  inspiration.  They  embody 
the  view  of  the  moment.  Their  value  is  mainly  a 
passing  one.  They  may  contain  documents  of  more 
than  passing  value,  treaties  or  agreements  or  plans 
which  have  subsequently  been  translated  into  action. 
But  as  material  out  of  which  a  scientific  and  lasting 
account  of  the  facts  can  be  reconstructed,  they  suffer 
from  inevitable  because  inherent  defects.  Ambas- 
sadors' letters  and  the  letters  written  to  them  are 
documents  in  which  the  impressions  of  the  moment 
are  recorded,  impressions  which  are  very  often 
evanescent.  Such  documents  are,  from  the  cir- 


2? 

cumstances  in  which  they  are  composed,  almost 
always  fragmentary  and  incomplete.  In  public  life 
the  point  of  view  is  constantly  changing.  If  a  hun- 
dred years  after  this  an  historian,  desiring  to  describe 
the  relations  between  Great  Britain  and  Germany, 
or  between  the  former  country  and  France,  in  the 
commencement  of  the  twentieth  century,  were  to 
confine  himself  to  the  State  papers  of  particular 
years,  he  would  be  misled.  He  would  see  little  to 
explain  the  rapid  evolution  and  change  that  had 
taken  place  within  a  very  brief  period.  Nor  could 
he  ever  discover  the  traces  of  almost  imperceptible 
and  rarely  recorded  influences  and  incidents  which 
had  stimulated  the  development.  This  is  true  of 
the  evolution  of  policy  at  home  as  well  as  abroad. 
Speaking  with  some  knowledge  of  what  has  gone  on 
from  day  to  day  during  the  last  eight  years  of  the 
public  life  of  this  country,  my  experience  has  im- 
pressed me  with  a  strong  feeling  that  to  try  to  recon- 
struct the  story  from  State  papers  or  newspaper 
accounts  or  letters  or  biographical  sources  would  be 
at  present,  and  must  for  some  time  remain,  a  hope- 
less attempt.  And  I  know  from  my  conversations 
with  men  of  still  longer  and  greater  experience  that 
they  hold  this  view  as  strongly  as  I  do.  The 
materials  so  afforded  must  be  used  at  a  later  period 
by  a  man  who  possesses  the  gifts  requisite  for  pre- 
senting the  narrative  as  that  of  an  organic  whole, 
/  and  that  organic  whole  must  in  its  expression  be  born 
afresh  in  his  mind.  So  only  will  he  present  a  picture 


28 

of  what  actually  happened  in  a  period  of  history. 
The  historian  will  fail  hopelessly  if  he  seeks  to  be 
a  mere  recorder.  For  the  truth  about  the  whole,  the 
expression  of  which  is  what  matters,  was  not  realised 
in  its  completeness  until  time  and  the  working  of  the 
spirit  of  the  period  had  enabled  the  process  de- 
veloped in  a  succession  of  particular  events  to  be 
completed.  It  is  a  mistake  to  suppose  that  states- 
men are  always  conscious  of  the  ends  which  they 
are  accomplishing.  It  is  not  by  the  piecing  together 
of  mechanical  fragments,  but  by  a  process  more  akin 
to  the  development  of  life,  that  societies  grow  and 
are  changed. 

There  is  thus,  if  I  am  right,  an  inevitable  element 
of  what  seems  at  first  sight  to  be  unreality  in  even 
the  best  work  of  historians.  But  this  need  not  dis- 
courage us  if  our  notion  of  reality,  and  therefore  of 
our  standard  of  truth,  is  something  more  than  the 
mere  correspondence  of  isolated  images  and  facts. 
If  the  test  of  truth  in  history  must  be  the  presentation 
ot  an  expression,  true  at  least  in  the  sense  in  which 
we  use  the  word  about  a  great  portrait,  then  the 
recording  of  the  chance  fragments  of  isolated  facts 
which  alone  have  survived  for  us  is  quite  inadequate 
to  the  fulfilment  of  the  test.  All  the  historian  writes 
ought  to  be  true  in  the  sense  of  being  a  faithful  and 
accurate  account  of  what  has  happened.  But  that 
does  not  mean  that  he  should  record  every  detail 
of  what  has  happened.  If  he  tries  to  do  this  he  will 
lose  both  his  real  subject  and  himself.  His  business 


29 

is  to  select  in  the  light  of  a  larger  conception  of  the 
truth.  He  must  look  at  his  period  as  a  whole  and 
in  the  completeness  of  its  development.  And  this 
is  a  task  rather  of  the  spirit  than  of  the  letter.  Those 
who  furnish  him  with  the  materials  have  not,  and 
cannot  have,  the  insight  which  is  requisite  for  him, 
if  he  is  to  be  a  great  historian  of  reality.  And  yet, 
of  course,  their  work,  if  it  is  well  done,  is  indis- 
pensable. It  is  indispensable,  only  it  is  not  history 
until  it  has  been  re-fashioned  in  the  mind  of  the 
historian.  When  a  really  competent  historian  has 
done  this  we  may  fairly  think,  Goethe's  scepticism 
notwithstanding,  that  real  history  is  possible,  inas- 
much as  we  see  before  us  the  picture  of  the  spirit 
of  the  past. 

I  now  turn  to  a  second  form  of  criticism,  that 
which  would  reject  as  inadmissible  the  intrusion  of 
art  into  the  domain  of  history.  Two  well-known 
authorities  on  its  study,  M.  Langlois  and  M.  Seig- 
nobos,  some  fifteen  years  ago  published  a  joint  book 
for  the  purpose  of  warning  their  students  at  the 
Sorbonne  what  the  study  of  history  ought  not  to  be, 
It  was  in  effect  an  essay  on  the  method  of  the  his- 
torical sciences.  It  is  interesting  to  observe  the 
result  at  which  they  arrived,  for  this  result  shows  the 
difficulties  into  which  anyone  is  bound  to  get  who 
adopts  their  conception  of  the  subject.  Broadly 
stated,  their  conclusion  is,  that  while  up  to  about  the 
middle  of  last  century  history  continued  to  be  treated 
as  a  branch  of  literature,  a  change  has  now  taken 


30 

place,  and  scientific  forms  of  historical  exposition 
have  been  evolved  and  settled,  based  on  the  general 
principle  that  the  aim  of  history  must  be,  not  to 
arouse  the  emotions  or  to  give  moral  guidance,  but  to 
impart  knowledge  pure  and  simple.  They  admit 
that  for  many  form  still  counts  before  matter,  and 
that  consequently  a  Macaulay  or  a  Michelet  or  a 
Carlyle  continues  to  be  read,  although  he  is  no 
longer  on  a  level  with  current  knowedge.  But  such 
writing  is  not,  according  to  them,  history  proper. 
What  is  justified  in  the  case  of  a  work  of  art  is  not 
justified  in  a  work  of  science.  And  the  methods  of 
the  older  historians  cannot,  they  therefore  hold,  now 
be  justified.  Thus,  they  say,  Thucydides  and  Livy 
wrote  to  preserve  the  memory  and  propagate  the 
knowledge  of  glorious  deeds  or  of  important  events, 
and  Polybius  and  Plutarch  wrote  to  instruct  and 
give  recipes  for  action.  Political  incidents,  wars, 
and  revolutions  were  in  this  fashion  the  main  theme 
of  ancient  history.  Even  in  our  own  time  they 
think  that  the  German  historians  have  adopted  the 
old  rejected  habits.  Mommsen  and  Curtius  they 
instance  as  authors  whose  desire  to  make  a  strong 
impression  has  led  them  to  a  certain  relaxation  of 
scientific  vigour.  Speaking  for  myself,  I  should  not 
have  been  surprised  had  they,  on  the  assumption  that 
their  severe  standard  is  to  be  adopted,  put  Treitschke 
in  particular  into  the  pillory,  for  he  was  a  very  great 
offender  against  their  precepts.  According  to  them, 
history  ought  to  be  in  the  main  a  science  and  not 


31 

an  art.  It  is  only  indirectly  that  it  should  possess 
practical  utility.  Its  main  object  should  be  accuracy 
in  recording.  It  consists  only,  so  they  say,  in  the 
utilisation  of  documents,  and  chance  therefore  pre- 
dominates in  the  formation  of  history,  because  it  is 
a  matter  of  chance  whether  documents  are  preserved 
or  lost.  But  they  admit  that  the  work  of  the  his- 
torian cannot  be  limited  by  the  bare  documentary 
facts  which  he  collects  himself.  To  an  even  greater 
degree  than  other  men  of  science  he  works  with 
material  which  is  to  a  large  extent  collected  by 
others.  These  may  have  been  men  who  devoted 
their  energies  to  the  task  of  search  and  collection, 
whose  work  has  merely  been  what  is  called 
"  heuristic."  Or  they  may  have  been  previous  his- 
torians. The  point  is  that,  as  the  knowledge  of  the 
historian  is  only  partially  derived  from  his  own  direct 
research,  his  science  is  one  of  inference  rather  than 
of  observation. 

It  is  a  corollary  from  the  view  of  truth  in  history 
which  I  have  just  been  quoting  that  it  should  reject, 
not  merely  all  efforts  to  look  for  the  hand  of  Provi- 
dence as  the  interpretation  of  human  development, 
but  also  the  attempts  which  have  been  made  in 
philosophies  of  history  to  see  in  it  the  evolution  of 
forms  of  mind.  Bossuet  and  Hegel  come  alike 
under  condemnation.  "  On  ne  s'arrete  plus  guere 
aujourd'hui  a  discuter,"  says  M.  Seignobos,  "sous 
la  forme  theologique  la  theorie  de  la  Providence 
dans  1'histoire.  Mais  la  tendance  a  expliquer  les 


32 

faits  historiques  par  les  causes  transcendantes  per- 
siste  dans  des  theories  plus  modernes,  ou  la  meta- 
physique  se  deguise  sous  des  formes  scientifiques." 
Now  there  is  no  doubt  much  to  be  said  for  the 
resolute  spirit  in  which  the  two  professors  of  the 
Sorbonne  set  themselves  to  eliminate  all  prejudices 
and  theories  and  methods  which  can  distract  from 
impartiality  and  exactness  of  description.  But  their 
own  admissions,  as  I  have  just  quoted  them,  about 
deficiency  in  material,  and  the  impossibility  of  his- 
tory being  a  science  of  pure  observation  as  dis- 
tinguished from  inference,  deprive  their  protest  of 
a  good  deal  of  its  value.  Without  going  as  far  as 
Goethe  went  in  his  scepticism  about  records,  it  is 
plain  that  the  business  of  selection  must  bulk  largely 
in  every  historical  undertaking.  And  that  is  why, 
while  rules  as  to  historical  evidence  such  as  the 
two  authors  lay  down  are  of  use  and  should  be 
adhered  to  wherever  it  is  possible,  the  historian  who 
confined  himself  within  what  alone  these  rules  allow 
would  produce  little  or  nothing.  The  necessity  of 
artistic  selection  from  materials  which  are  admittedly 
imperfect,  not  to  speak  of  the  personal  equation  of 
the  writer,  would  make  a  history  founded  on  merely 
scientific  methods  a  mockery.  History  belongs  to 
the  region  of  art  at  least  as  much  as  it  does  to  that 
of  science,  and  this  is  why,  -pace  M.  Seignobos,  we 
shall  continue  to  delight  in  Michelet  and  Macaulay 
and  Carlyle,  and  to  insist  on  regarding  their  books 
as  among  the  world's  most  valuable  records.  They 


33 

are  presentations  by  great  artists  of  the  spirit  of  a 
period,  and  the  artists  are  great  because  with  the 
power  of  genius  they  have  drawn  portraits  which 
we  recognise  as  resembling  the  results  of  direct 
perception.  Genius  has  been  called  the  capacity 
for  taking  pains  that  is  infinite,  and  these  men  have 
taken  immeasurable  pains  and  have  been  inspired 
by  a  passion  for  truth  according  to  their  lights.  Of 
course,  they  have  selected  and  refashioned  the 
materials  which  through  close  research  were  first 
collected,  as  great  artists  always  must.  Doubtless, 
too,  there  are  aspects  which  they  have  left  out  or 
left  over  for  presentation  by  other  artists.  But  por- 
traits may,  as  we  have  seen,  vary  in  expression  and 
yet  be  true,  for  the  characteristic  of  what  is  alive 
and  intelligent  and  spiritual  is  that  it  may  have 
many  expressions,  all  of  which  are  true.  With  what 
is  inert  and  mechanical,  it  is  for  certain  purposes 
different,  but  what  is  inert  and  mechanical  is  the 
subject  neither  of  the  artist  nor  the  historian.  It  is 
because  they  let  themselves  go  in  bringing  out  the 
expression  of  life  and  personality  that  we  continue 
to  cling  to  Gibbon  and  Mommsen.  Their  problem 
is  to  display  before  us  the  course  of  the  lives  of 
men  and  of  nations.  Men  and  nations  cannot  be 
estimated  through  the  medium  of  the  balance  and 
the  measuring-rod  alone,  nor  are  these  the  most 
important  instruments  for  estimating  them.  The 
phenomena  which  belong  to  the  region  of  the  spirit 
can  be  interpreted  only  through  the  medium  of  the 

14360  c 


34 

spirit  itself.  We  cannot  interpret  by  mechanical 
methods  a  play  of  Shakespeare  or  a  sonata  of 
Beethoven.  In  the  regions  of  life  and  personality 
the  interpretation  must  come  through  life  and  per- 
sonality, and  the  mind  recognises  the  truth  of  their 
interpretation  when  it  recognises  in  it  what  accords 
with  its  own  highest  phases.  History  is  not  mere 
imagination.  It  must  always  rest  on  a  severely- 
proved  basis  of  fact.  But  no  mere  seventy  of  proof 
will  give  the  historian  even  this  basis.  The  judg- 
ment of  truth  implies  a  yet  higher  standard  of  com- 
pleteness and  perfection. 

I  am  therefore  unable  to  agree  with  those 
who  think  that  history  must  be  either  exclusively 
a  science  or  exclusively  an  art.  It  is  a  science  to  the 
extent  to  which  what  are  commonly  known  as  scien- 
tific methods  are  requisite  for  accuracy  and  proper 
proportion  in  the  details  used  in  the  presentation. 
But  the  presentation  must  always  be  largely  that  of 
an  artist  in  whose  mind  it  is  endowed  with  life  and 
form.  Truth  in  history  requires,  in  order  to  be  truth 
in  its  completeness,  that  the  mind  of  the  reader 
should  find  itself  satisfied  by  that  harmony  and 
sense  of  inevitableness  which  only  a  work  of  art 
can  give.  Abstractness  of  detail  and  absence  of 
coherence  offend  this  sense  of  harmony,  and  so 
offend  against  truth  by  incompleteness  of  presenta- 
tion. The  reader  feels  that  the  facts  must  have 
appeared,  at  the  period  in  which  they  did  really 
appear,  in  a  fashion  quite  different.  Unless  the 


35 

history  which  he  reads  gives  him  something  of  a 
direct  sense  of  the  presence  of  the  actual,  his  assent 
will  be  at  the  most  what  Cardinal  Newman  called 
notional  as  distinguished  from  real.  To  define  the 
meaning  of  truth  in  history  thus  becomes  a  problem 
that  is  difficult,  because  it  is  complex.  But  this  at 
least  seems  clear,  that  some  notions  about  this  mean- 
ing that  have  been  current  in  days  gone  by,  and  are 
still  current,  ought  to  be  reconsidered.  A  clear  con- 
ception of  first  principles  is  essential  in  most  things, 
and  not  least  in  the  writing  of  history.  If  I  have 
succeeded  in  rendering  plain  to  you  the  reasons 
which  make  me  feel  this  need  strongly,  I  shall  have 
accomplished  all  that  I  ventured  to  hope  for  on  the 
present  occasion. 


PRINTED   FOR  THE   UNIVERSITY   OF   LONDON    PRESS,    LTD.,    BY 

RICHARD   CLAY    AND   SONS,    LIMITED, 

LONDON   AND   BUNGAY. 


19 


ONE  D  !" 


14  DAY  USE 

RETURN  TO  DESK  FROM  WHICH  BORROWED! 

LOAN  DEPT. 

This  book  is  due  on  the  last  date  stamped  below,  or 

on  the  date  to  which  renewed. 
Renewed  books  are  subject  to  immediate  recall. 


SSI 

i  -  - 

aSNIar'SSlSk. 

REC'D  LD 

MAR  2  3®: 

1 

LD  21-100m-6,'56 
(B9311slO)476 


General  Library 

University  of  California 

Berkeley 


YB  21880