Skip to main content

Full text of "mibok"

See other formats


Philosopl^ 6f Religion in the 21st Century 



Ciiiremont Studies in the Philosophy ofRdi^ion 

Genera] Editors: D. Z. Phillips, Rush Rhees Research Proff^swjr. Uni^^ersSl^ibt 
Wale?^, ^iv^nsea and Dan^orth Pfofessor of the Philosophy of Reiigio]!^ the 

Claremont GiatJuate School^ California; Timothy Tcs.sin 

At a tJme^vhen discussions of reiigion are becoming increasingly s^ectalizeJ and 
determmed by religious affiliations^ at 1^ ampoTtant to mdintain a forum for 

philosophical discussion ^vhich transcejitl^ the allegiances oJ l>[^lief and unbelief. 
Thts series affords aai opportunity" for philosophers of ^videEy differing 
persuasions to explore central issues in Clie philosophy of rehgion. 

Tlti^s mciuiii^: 

Stephen T Davis (f t/jtt?r> 

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOCi[CAL DISCOURSE. 

D- Z- Philips {etiilon 

CAN RELIGION EEEXPLAENED AWAY? 

D_ Z_ Philips andTimothy Tessin (cJjro?:s) 
KA^"^ AND KEERKEGAARD ON RELIGION 
PHILOSOPHY Ol- RELIGION IN THE 2LST tIEMTURY 
RLLKiK)N WETHOUT TRANStZENDENCE? 
RELIGION AND HUME-S LEGACY 

Timothy Tessin and Mario von der Ruhr \trtiitofs) 
PHILOSOPHY AND THE GRAMMAR Ot RELIGIOUS BELIEF 



Strits SitjndinH <Jrdtr ]Sli^ (f-lili :i-7i 46?^-2 
{OutirJc Ntiriii A*fit'riia only) 

ViiHi am recdvc future tiilc^ in this series a^ tht^v' art: published by pladn^ ^ ^t^nding <yrdtt. 
Mtast contact your bookseller or, in iiast oi dilffit^Ety, Write to ui dt tt]t addrtfiS !>t(ow Witt] 
yuur naitjc Lj]Ld aJdFLsS, tlic tatltoJ thi: StrtCit and fEii; JlifiN quoted aS>ove_ 

Cuj>tuB]iLi Scrh'lLiJij D^i^ei rti[iiL'[]t, KlLicchilJikEi Distribution Ltd. llonjciJitiilLiir Bjliji [i^i^taLt:^ 



Philosophy of Rehgion in 
the 21st Century 



Edited bv 

D.Z. Phillips 

Dnufvrih Froft^ssor of Pliihsoptiy of Re!i^oi\^ Chjremonl Gnuliutt^ Uiu\^rsity 
ami Rush Rhees Research I^ofessor^ U^m^ersity of Wahs>^ Swansea 

and 

TiiTkothy Tiissui 



palgrave 




©TtieClaremofit Crarfuate School Z0O1 

All rights reserved- No reproductior. -copy or tranimisEion of 
tKi5 publication may b-e made without written pernn^ssion. 

No paragraph of this publication maybe reproduce-d, copied or 
transmitted save with written permiision or in accordance with 
the provisions of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 19es. 
or under ttie terms of any licence permitting limited copying 
issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency, 90 Tott-en ham Court 
Road, London WIT 4LP- 

Any person whodoes any unauthorised act in relation to this 
publication may be liable to criminal prosecution and civil 
claims for damages. 

Ttie authors have asserted their rights to be identified 
as the authors of this work in accor<tance vjilh the 
Copyright. Designs and Patents Act 1986. 

First published Z001 by 
PALGRAVf 

Houndmills. Basjngsfeke^^mpshire RG21 6X5 and 

175 fifth Avenue. New Y^rk.N.Y-lOOlO 

Companies and representatives throughout the world 

PALGRAVE is the new global academic imprint of 

5t. Martjn-5 Press LLC Scholarly and Reterence Division and 

Pslgrave Publishers Lid [formerly Matmillan Press Ltd). 

I5BN 0"33S-^BO-] 75-X hardback 

This book is printed on paper suitable for recycling and 
marfe from fully managed and sustained forest sources. 

A catalogue record for this book ts av^Plabte 
from the British Library. 

Library of Congress Catalo^ng-in-Publication Data 
Philosophy of religion in the 21st century / edited by D. Z. Phillips 
and Ti mothy Tessin. 
p. cm. 
Includes bibliographical references and index. 

15BrMt>-333-a0175-X [cloth) 

1 . Re ligion^Ph ilosop hy. 1. PhitCips. D_ Z_ [Dewi Zephani ah) 
ILTessinrTimothy- ML Series. 



BL51.P53+ZO0T 
Z10— dcZl 



10 987654321 
10 09 08 07 06 05 04 OB 02 01 



ZOO 103+500 



Pnnled and bound in Great BritiBin by 
Antony Rowe Ltd^ Chippeniiam^ Wiltshire 



Contents 




1 


A ckf lowiedxL'maits 


vLi 


1 


Notes ofi the Contfibutors 


viii 


1 


lutjodiictiof} 


xi 


1 


Part I Philosophical Theism 

_ _ ^ _ 


1 


1 


1 ^hi osophLcal Theism 


■3: 


1 


Ridmnf Swinbtinie 




1 


2 Phi osophica] Theology at the End of the Centufy 


21 


1 


WilUam [. Wninwngiit 




1 


3 Voices in Discussion 


31 


1 


D.Z.PhiU!ps 




1 


Part II Rtftinntd Episteiiioiogj^ 


37 


1 


4 Rcforine<J fepistcniology 


39 


1 


Nidioliii WttitcFstorff 




1 


5 On Behalf of the Evidcntialist - a Response to 




1 


WolEcrstorff 


64 


1 


Stephen). Wykst3{\ 




1 


6 Voices in Discussion 


85 


1 


D.Z. mtisps 




1 


Part III Wittgtnitein and Wittgensteinianism 


93 


1 


7 Wittgenstein and the Philosophy of Religion 


95 


1 


Staphm MiiihaH 




1 


S Wittgenstein and tlie Philosophy of Religion: 




1 


a Reply to Stephen Nlulhall 


119 


1 


Walfoni Gealy 




1 


9 Voices Ht'i^ei^on 


144 


1 


D.Z. Piiiltips 




1 


V 




J 



vi Cfl/ifmts 




1 


Pari IV Postnio tier n ism 


151 


1 


10 Mcsstantc Postmodernism 


15:? 


1 


foisfs D. Caputo 




1 


11 The Oihcr without History and Society - a Dialogic 




1 


with Dcrrida 


167 


1 


Anselrn Kyon^sak Mhi 




1 


12 Voices In Discussion 


186 


1 


D.Z. Phiiiips 




1 


Part V Critltal Tlit-ory 


191 


1 


13 Critical Theory and Religion 


193 


1 


Miitthkis Liitz-Ikidummii 




1 


14 Critical Theory and Religion 


211 


1 


Mneve Cooka 




1 


15 Voices Ln Discussion 


244 


1 


D.Z. Phillip!; 




1 


Pari VI Process Thought 


249 


1 


1 6 Ptocess Thought 


251 


1 


foisis R Cobb, /r 




1 


17 Process Thouglit - a Response to John B. Cobb, Jr 


266 


1 


Schubert M. Osiien 




1 


18 Voices in Discussion 


281 


1 


D.Z. PhiUipa 




1 


19 Voices in Discussion 


28& 

_ , _ _ p 


1 


D.Z. Phimps 




1 


Index 


291 


J 



Acknowledgements 



I Am happy (o acknowledge the financial support given to llie 
Conference by Clarcinont Graduate University^ Pomona Collcj^c and 
Qaremont McKcnna College. I am grateful Eo the partlelpants who 
contributed to the funding of future conferences by waiving their 
claim lo royallies. Admtiiistratively, I acn indebted to Helen Baldwin 
and Jackie Huntzingcr^ secretaries to the Department; of Philosophy at 
the Unlvcrsily of WalcSj Swansea and lo the Department of Religion aE 
Clarcinont Graduate University^ respectively. Graduate students helped 
during the conference In transporting ihe parlicipanls to various 
venues. They were organized by my abJe research, assistant Richard 
Amcsbury, who was also responsible fot tyj^ing my Introduction and 
the various Voices In discussion'_ I am cxtremf^iy grateful to him for his 
help in this and other contoLts. Finally, I thank my co-editor Tiinolhy 
Tessin for proof-reading the collection and for seeing it through its 
various stages of publicalion. 

D.Z.P. 



vJl 



Notes on the Contributors 



John B. Cobh, Jr is Profos^or Emeritus of Theology at the Cteremont 
School ofThcology ^^^^ of Religion at Clarcmont Graduate University. 
He continues as co^dlrcctoi of llio Ccnlrc for Process Studies. Among 
his books arc A Chrhtitu! Naturai Theology Based on the Thought of Alfred 
North Whitehead, Christ in {i Pim^ilistic Age, The Striscture of Chnj;thm 
Existence, Process Tfieolo^': an Jfitrod:ictory Exposition (with David 
GrLtfinj, The Liberation of Life (wLlh Charles Birch). 

Maeve f^ookc is Senior Lecturer in the Department of Gciman at 

University Colk^^e, Dublin. She is the author of Lan^nugi.' iwd Reason: a 
Study of Haberm^s^:? Pnigmatics and editor of a collection of Habernias's 
writings on language and communicatiDn: On the Prtigrnt^tics of 
Cotfununicatioii. 

John D. Caputo is David R. Cook Professor of Philosophy at Villanova 
University- He is the author of The Prayers atid Tears off^eqaes Dtrrida: 
Reli^iofi without Religion, Decom^tfuetion hi a Nntsh^U: a Conversation witfi 
facques DerridHj, Radiad Hcrm^netitics: Repetition^ Deconstriatiofiy and tise 
Hermefteiitic Project, Against Ethics: Contrlhtttions to a Pttetics ofONi^ution 
with Con 5ta}st Reference to Dcconstiuction, DemytJ!oio^izhsg Helde^er. 

Walford Gealy was Senior Lecturer in the Department of Extra-Mural 

Studies at University of Wales^ Aberystwyth. He is the author oi 
Witt^i'f}stein, written in Welsh, and co-editor of the journal EfiydiiUi 
AtimmyJdoi (PliLiosophlcal Studies). He Is the autitor of over fifty artl- 
cles, most of them tact ng in Welsh, his native language. 

Ma Ltliias Lutz-fiachniatin is Pro fessor of Phi t osophy at Goe t he- 
University in Franl^furt^ Gertmany. His puhlications include Kritisclfe 

nieone and Rciision, l^ietaphysUcktitik-Ethiia-'ReUsion (editorj, frieden dnreh 
Reciit fco-editorln and Perpetna! Pence: Ei^says on Kant^s Cosmopolitan Ideal 
(co-editor). 

Anselm Kyonf^suk Min is Professor of Religion and Theology at 

Clareniont Graduate University. He is the author of Dialectic of 
Salvation: Issues if} Theolo^' of Liberation. He is currently working on a 

new theological paradigm^ Solidarity of OthcrSj as a theology after 
postmodernism. 



vliS 



JVc?fe.^ ow the Conthbuiars ix 

Stephen MuLhalL is a PgIIow and Tutor in Philosophy at New College, 

Oxford- J lis recent publications include Fuiti! and Reujion^ He'uii^g^Tt ami 
^Beif^ tmd Tsmc\ and The CaveU Rctfder (cdMoi:). 

Schiihcrt M. O^dcn is University Distinguished Professor of Theo^o^ 
Emeritus^ Southern \iethodi5t University, liis most recent books 
Include Is Tli^re Only One Ttue Religion or Are Then' Many? And Doing 
Tlieology Toddy. 

D.Z. Phillips is Danforth Professor of the Philosophy of Religion, 

Clareinoiit Gradu^TLc UniversiLy and [tush Rhees Research Professor, 
University of Wales^ Swansea. He is the author of The Concept ofPniyei', 
Faith and PfnIo:ii}pi!fi:ai Enquiry, Death ami Iinnwttafity, Morn} Pnictices 
(with H-O- Mouncc), Sense and Ddnsion (with 11 ham Dilman), 
Athi'onyddn Ans Grefyihi, Rdigion without Exphuiatht}, Dnnmu Owaniyn 
Piirr}\ Beliefs Change and Fonfis of Ufe, Through a Darkenhig Giass, 
RS. Tiiomns: Foet of the lildda^ Gtfii, F^iith after Foundatitmaiiiin, From 
Fantasy to Faith, Interventions in Ethics, Wittgenstein and Reiigion, Writers 
of Wales: J.R. fones, Lstroducing Riiiiosophy, Recoi'erifig Religious Concepts^ 
Philosophy's Cool Place. He is editor of i^i'tiii^fj Studies in Philosophy and 
co-editor of Chiremont Studies in the Philosophy ofReiigion piLblishcd by 
Patgrave. He is also editor of the journal. Philosophical hivesti^ationa. 

Rjehard Swhihurtie is Nolloth Professor of the Philosophy of the 
Christian Rehgion at the University of Oxford^ and a Fellow of the 
British Academy. He is the author of Space and Time, an It^trodtu^tion to 
Confirmation Theory, The Coherence of Theism, The Existence of God, Faith 
and Reason, The Evolution of the Sotd. Responsib'tiity and Atonement, 
Reveiation, The Christian God^ Is There a God?, Providence and tlie Probieni 
of Evil. 

Tlinothy Tessin [s co-editor of Philosophy ami the Grammar ofRdigicus 
Belief He is also co-editor of Ciaremont Stiulies in the Philosophy of 
Religion and associate editor of Philosophical huestigations. 

V^W^m }. Wainwrisht is Distin^lshed Professor of Philosophy at 
the University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee- His publications include 
Philosophy of Religion: an Amwtated Bibliography, Mysticism, Philosophy of 
Religion, Reason and tlxe Heart, God, Philosophy and Academic Culture. He 
Is a former editor of Faith and Philosophy. 

Mchotas Wolterstorff is Noali Porter Professor of Philosophical 
Theology Emeritus at Vale Divinity School and was adjunct professor in 
the Departments of Philosophy and Religious Studies. He is the author 



of Works and Worlds of Art, Art in Action^ Rea^ort within the Limits of 
Relighnj^ fohi Locke and tJw Ethks ofHeiiif, Di\^ine Di!^coijrse l\99^ Wilde 
Lectures ar Oxford), Until fustice nnd Peace Embrace, Religion m the Fui?ifc 
Square, and World, fvliad ^wd Entltiement to Believe {199^ Gifford Lectures 
at St Andrews) and Thorrtas Reid and tiie Story of Epsj^terr^oh^. He has 
been PrcsidcnL of the American Philosophical AssocLalLon (Central 
Division) and of the Socicly of Christian Plii!o5oplicrs. 

Stephen T- Wykstra is Professor of Philosophy at Cahln College. He 
has ptihlishcd articles in history and philosophy of science, and in the 
philosophy of fcli^Lon. 



Introduction 

D.Z. PhUiips 



The syinposm and discussions picscnicd here represent the proceedings 
of the 1999 anniial philosophy of religion conference which took place 
at Clarcinont Graduate Unlvcislty- Previous publlcaLioiis in the scries 
Clarcmont Studies In the Philosophy of Reltj^ion are: Philosophy and the 
Gnmumn of Reli^hus Belief; Rdi^iofs ami Kioniiityy Cnn Rciigioii Bt 
Exphiine^i Aw^y7; Religion without T^iI^sce}ld^!I€e?; Rehsion and Hmne^s 
LegiKiy; and Kwit amf Kk^rkegaani sm Rt^iigio^i. k was thought appropriate 
in 1999 to prepare tor the year 2000 by presenting a volume on the 
present state of philosophy of rehgion. It was impossil:?le to include 
evcryilihig, so choice was made on the basis of movements wlilch it 
was thouglit had to be represerLtcd, On the other hand, the conference 
was arranged with consLdcrablc trepidation^ since tlicrc was always the 
danger that tlic six philosophical schools wojid pass each other by like 
ships in the night. The message in my Thai fortune-cookie, opened in 
the closing banquet of the conference, would have summed up my 
foreboding at its outset. Ic read, 'Vou would be wise not to seek too 
much from others at this time/ For once my fortune- cookie w-as not 
uncannily revelatory since, as the discussions reveal^ genuine attempts 
were made to probe and explore difficulties connected wUh each point 
of view. I am not Roing to rehea:sc these in this introduction. Instead, 
I am going to single out a feature of the conference which struck me 
most forcibly as its organizer 

Tlic papers in the conference represent, not simply differences on 
specific topics, but differences concerning the very conception of philo- 
sophical enquiry. In one sense, it would be foolish to try to determine 
the nature of philosophy since, descriptively, this w^ould be a hitile exer- 
cise. Wliy insist that philosophy or philosophy of religion can only be 
done in one way^ when it is obviously practised in a number of ways? 



*1 



xii Introduction 

It is tempting to take a [olcram attitude and simply say 'Lci a thousand 
flowers bloom/ liut^ in another scnse^ ihat cannot be allowed withouL 
denying a considerable part of plitlosoph>''s history^ Tliis is Ijecausc the 
nature of philosopliy is itself a philosophical question and great 
philosophers have bt^^n critical o( thdr pjcdcccssors' conception of ihc 
subject. 

In the papers in this collection we are presented with marked differ- 
ences in one's coneepLlon of the tasks which philosophy of religion 
can and should peiforin. 

According to Richard Swinburne, philosophy of religion has^ at its 
heartr the rational assessment of religious beliefs. They are to be assessed^ 
as he would say any belief must, in terms of the probability of their 
being true. Swinburne holds that the truth and rationality of religious 
beliefs can be assessed in this way. 

While WilliaiTL Wainwright is generally sympathetic to SwLn[:Jurne, he 
is sceptical about the efficacy of probabiliLy arguments for most educated 
audiences today. This is because, he ar^jies^ we need a properly disposed 
lieart in order to assess the evidence- The vital issue^ as VVainwright 
recognizes, then becomes one of showing how these antecedent judge- 
nicnts are related to the evidence on has to consider. 

Nicholas Woltcrstorf f coi^dones Reformed Epistcmology's rejection ol 
the Enlightenment ideal of a rational religion. Something does not 
have to be grounded in ojrder to be rational. As a result of a world- 
transforming cjcpcrience, the Christian philosopher in tliis tradition 
offers, not a philosophy of religion^ but a religious philosophy, its aim 
is to see all aspects of tiuman life, intellectual and non-intellectual, in 
the light of faith. It docs not subject religion to the test of so-called 
neutral evidence. 

Stephen Wykstra wonders whether this rejection of cvidentialisTn 
itself comes from a too narrow conception of evidence, namely; inferen- 
tial evidence. He hnds the rejection unrealistic in a world in which faith 
is challenged in maity ways. It may not be necessaiy for an individual 
believer to consider Lhcse challenges in detail^ but unless someone in 
the coinmunity does so, he argues, it is too easy eo see faith as slniply 
-l?urying onp's head in the sand. One is robbed of th& much-nEcded 
resources one has to Ljrn to in face of Lhcsc challenges. 

Stephen Mulhall In expounding Wittgenstein on religion and 
Wittgcnstcinianism, emphasizes the contemplative character of philo- 
sophical enquiry- The main interest here is in giving a just account of reli- 
gious belief by seeing to it that it is not confused with beliefs of another 
kind. This inteiesi: iiselT has a demanding ethic and is connected, he 



claims^ with a cert.iin kind of spiritual concern in ihc enquirer. This is 
because wc cannot be true to ourselves unless we are true to our words. 

Walford Gealy emphasizes that some of \"\^irtgenstein"'s early remarks 
on religion take the form ihat they do because of views of language he 
held at the time and which he rejected later. This should be remembered 
when these remarks are discussed. Like Mulhall, Gealy too argues thai 
the charge that Wittgenstein i a ns hold that religion is immune to criti- 
cism is absurd. Both writers give examples to counter this charge. On the 
other hand^ he insists that whatever is meant by spirituality in philo- 
sophical enquiry, this should not be compared with religious spirituality. 
Philosophy's concerns come from its own problems and puzzlements. 

John -Caputo emphasizes postmodernism's rejection of the 
Enlightenment dream of universal reason. We muse recognize that 'rea- 
son' means something different in different modes of thou^^hE and at 
different times and places. We must not seek a premature closure on 
questions of meriting and value. Some have scen^ in L>crrida, a form- 
less, chaotic, openness to everything in these emphases. Caputo denies 
this and sees in Derrida^s opeiiness a concern with fustice for the ollicrj 
which involves listening to what wc do not want to hear, the prepared- 
ness to be liurprised^ and to take risks in i^uch encounters. 

Ansctm Min is more sceptical about these latter claims, seeing in 
Derridaj the constant appeal to openness as being uninformed by spe- 
cific moral or political values. In emphasizing the tmpossibUity of 
arriving at a final statement of justice, something Min endorses, there 
Is the danger of the dream of the impossibie ttjrning us aside irom tlie 
actions that are required of us now. 

Again, in expoundiitg critical theor}^, Matthias Lutz-Bachmann 
ctnphasizes its rejection of the objectifying tendency one finds In meta- 
physics. Reasoning knows no absolute. Yetj Horkhcimer and Habermas 
want to invoke 'tlie unconditional' as a regulative ideal that calls us on to 
Improve the worlds without any conception of a. final goal. Religion may 
assist this task at certain times, but this is a contmgent facL Religion is 
replaceable by secular hopes for a better world. Lately, Habermas has 
come to sec that religious meanings may be sui generis, irreducible to 
any secular substitute. Lutz-Bachmann argues^ however^ tliat as long as 
Habermas bases human progress^ not on values, but on what human 
interests happen to be, he cannot avail himself of any positive concep- 
tion of justice. 

Maeve Cooke recognizes the lensioits in Habermas's thought which 
Lulz-liachmann emphasizes. He wants his conception of truth to be 
pragmatic and yet absolute. It is difficult to sec how rcUgious tnjth can 



xiv Introikiction 

bo accommodated In his system, she argues^ because his criteria of vin- 

dication demand piLblicly assessable c\^dcncc and a public agreement^ 
which is hard to iina^Lnc in the case of religious belief. 

John Cohh emphasizes the ivay in which Process Thought calls ihe 
assumptions of classical metaphysics Into question. It argues that 
'becoming' is more fundamental than 'being' and that 'events' are more 
fundamental than 'substances'. Following Whitehead, Cobb argues Ehat 
science is the tnosi fehabie guide lo what wc are given, as long as it is 
not permeated by the assumptions of classical metaphysics. Religion 
explores the more subjective side ot human nature. 

Cobb is sceptical about the possibility of neutral philosophy. Foi himn 
any Olympian height Is such within a system. Thus he acknowledges 
that his Process system has its presuppositions and that these play a 
vital role not only in the assessment of data^ but in the very possibility 
of seeing the data In a certain way_ 

Schubert Ogdcn insists that although philosophy is motivated by the 
existential questions concerning the meaning of existence, it is not 
constituted by them. Its task is to elucidate the necessary conditions of 
human discourse, and to reflect on the meanings which discourse actu- 
ally has. This latter task Includes rellectton on the dLstinclive claims of 
Christianity, one in which philosophy and theology come together. 
Ogden thinks that the existential questions and theologicai reflections 
are furthered best in Process thought. On one central issue, however^ 
he differs from most Process philosophers and theologians. They, 
Whitehead and Hartshorne included^ treat the conditions for the possi- 
bility of discourse^ or ultimate reality, as though these were a further 
5uper-fact. This confusion is found when myth is treated as a fact or 
when God, as ultimate reality, is treated as though it were a fact. ""God 
exists' is not a statement of fact. 

It is clear from this brief survey of points of view represented in this 
collection that there are wide differences between them in their con- 
ception of philosophy. In some ways, the Wlttgenstelnian tradition of 
contemplative philosophy seems an odd one out, but w-ould claim to 
l)c as old as Plato. In what sense does philosophy investigate reality? If, 
like the Presocr.itics, we try to give substantive account? of 'the rcaT in 
terms of, for example^ water or aloms^ ihc problem arises of what account 
can be given of the reality of the water or atoms. Plato came to see that a 
philosophical account of reality cannot lead to answers of that kind. The 
philosophical interest is a conceptual one; the question of what it means 
to distinguish l>etween the rcai or the unreal. Ihu.-i, on this view, philoso- 
phy is not Itself a ^vay of reaching the substantive judgements, but an 



enquiry into what iE means to reach conclusions of this kind. Unlike 
Plato, Wittgenstein did not think that this question admitted of a sin- 
gle answer. Hence his promise to teach us differences. 

This perspective raises questions about Swinhiirtic^s assuniptloii that 
all behefs are matters of probability. Are all beliefs of the same kind? Is 
belief in generosity the expression of a conviction or a matter of proha- 
bility? Further^ is it a mere probability that we had a Conference at 
Clarcniont? If I could be convinced otherwise would J sav that 1 had 
miscalculated probabilities^ or that 1 was ;^oing insane? Is trusting God 
a probability? 

W^illiam Wafnwri^ht is bothered^ too^ by some of these questions. He 
emphasizes that we make antecedent judgements in terms of which we 
see the data wc are to assess. How are these antecedent judgements to be 
understood? The suggestion that w-e can make them wlien our faculties 
are working property seems a Lime analogy, since, normally^ the notion 
of 'proper functioning' is normative and, in that sense, independent of 
tlic individual. Further, there is usually agreement on the notion of 
proper functioning, as the case of eyesight illustrates. Is Lt like this in 
the case of the clash between belief and unbelief? 

There is another difficulty which relates to the contemplative conccp 
tion of philosophy. U what can be seen is linked to the personal appro- 
priation of the perspective in question^ or to the ""proper functioning^ 
of faculties, how Is it possible to contemplate, and give an accouiit of, 
different perspcctivci? Further, someone who docs not embrace a per- 
spectivc may give a better pliiiosophical account of its character than 
one who docs not embrace it. 

In Reformed Epistemology a world-transforming religious experience 
is at the toot of the religiously orientated philosophical vocation to sec 
tlic world in the light of faith. Obviously, such a use can be made of 
philosophy, or this is what philosophy can amount to for someone, but 
what is its relation to the contemplative conception of philosophy? Can 
It admit that a non-beiievcr can give a better philosophical accoLtnt of 
religious belief than a believer? What sort of claim docs a religious 
philosophy make? Is it a theoretical claim? If something is seen in the 
light of faith, how is that 'seeing' related to other non-rehgious 'sceings'? 
Can there be a philosophical interest In these differences wliich is not 
a further form of such 'seeing^? 

In Postmodernism and in Critical Theory wc have attacks on the 
ambitions of a universal metaphysics, and a recognition of differences. 
The question arises, however^ wliether in the ethical concerns of Dcrrida 
or Habermas, an ethical insight is appropriated which cannot be derived 



xva Introduction 

from their phiiosophical critique. Having abolished a universal meta- 
physics, there scctn^ to be a desire to replace U with an attitude which 
is equally universal even when Lt calls itself ^^open' and denies the pos- 
sibiUty of closure. 

Again^ in Process Thought^ we have a similar attack ou classical meta- 
physics. This attack may be upheld in many respects, but questions may 
be asked as to wlicthcf one set of ulrimates, 'becoming^ and 'events' has 
now replaced another, Also, as Cobb admits, eertaiii presuppositions are 
'l>rought to bear on the data in interpreting them and he denies the 
possibility of a neutral philosophy. Does this mean that Process 
Thought can argue against this possibility? If so, there is at least one 
pcrspecllvc It seems to deny when, at other times^ It seems to recognize 
a plurality of systems of interpretation. Ogdcn says that Process 
Thought is the best theological system in answering central existential 
questions about the meaning of existcnce_ How would this be argued 
in relation lo different theological and atheistic perspectives? Are they 
shown to be conceptually confused in some sense? 

Ogdcn recognizes, along with Wittgcnsteinians, that the investigation 
of the conditions of discourse is not an investigation of some super-fact. 
On the other hand, he speaks of the necessary conditions of discourse. 

00 they form a single class? He also speaks of God as 'uUtmate reality', 
and says ihat ihis^ too, docs not refer to a matter of fact. How is this 
notion of reality related to the necessarv^ conditions of discourse? Arc 
they the same? If so, as in the case of Reformed Epistcmologj', here, 
too, we would have a religious conception of reality. 

These questions are prompted by philosophical considerations which 
axe familiar to students of Wittgenstein, but questions can be asked ol 
Wittgensteinianistn too. Is the anato^ between language and games 
an adequate one? After all, all games do not make up one big gamc^ 
whereas all language ;^ames occur within the same language. What 
account is to be given of the unity or identity of language? Does that 
lead back to a single account of reality? Without such an account is not 
the sense of life and living compartmentalized in unacceptable waj^? 

The questions asked of Wittgensteintanism can and have been 
addressed, for example, by Rush Rbces. No doubt the questions I have 
asked of the other points ol view can and have been addressed too. 

1 mention them here as questions with which the conference meeting 
left us. TIiuSh this introduction gives an indication^ not of where we 
started, but of the points at which we would have liked to have gone on. 

If philosophical enquiry is conceptual and contemplative, and recog- 
nizes the conceptual variety In human discourse, no single account of 



reality can be given. The enquiry will be molivaled by wonder at the 
ivorld ^nd the desire lo do justice to Its variety in the account we ^tvc. 
For others^ this is the road to relativism and they seek a religious concep- 
tion of reality whicli, in some way, can be shown to be more rational 
thai^i any secular akcrnativc. Altcmativelyj there iirc those who argue 
that allhougli tlie sense of things is open to a change and development 
to which philosophy cannot assign a closure, that development is itself 
to be informed by certain ethical and polltieal values. 

Perhaps one major difference which needs to be explored is this: are 
all perspectives on reality interpretations or expressions of interest, or 
Is there such a tiling in philosophy as disinterested enquiry? [s disinter- 
ested inquiry anotlier interest, alongside others^ Tcllgious and secular, 
or is it a different kind of interest, an interest m the variety of those 
religious and secular interests and the relation between rhem? Is an 
Olympian view alw^ays one from within some system or other? 

Many of the participants expressed the view at the end of the confer- 
ence that we needed to address these issues further If we did so in 
another conference^ perhaps its topic would be: Presuppositions. 



Finally, a word is necessary concerning the ^Voices in Discussion'. 
These are notes I took In the course of the discussions which followed 
each session- They do not purport to be absolutely accurate, although 
I have aimed at reporting the course of arguments as closely as possible. 
This is why the names of speakers have not been used. Readers of pre- 
vious volumes have had some fun In identifying the speakers. In the 
case of the participants this is not difficult because they be^in each 
discussion. Some reviewers were puzzled by the fact that the number 
of speakers outnumbered the participants. This is truer than ever on 
this occasion. This is because those wiio chair the session need not be 
paper-readers. Also^ at the end of each session discussion was opened 
up to the wider audience present. Reviewers have w^elcomed 'V^otccs 
In Discussion' as an addition to the collection, so I have decided to 
continue this practice. No account has been taken, of course, of any 
revisions made to the papers after the conference. 

My major aim in the conferences 1 organize is to brin^ together 
representatives of widely differing views, so keeping alive an older 
tradition in the philosophy of religion which, sadly, has declined. 
I only hope that the result of their discussions proves as valuable for 
readers as it did for those of us who participated in them. 



Parti 

Philosophical Theism 



1 



Philosophical Theism 

Richard Swmbuitie 



1 History of the jjro^rainmfi 

I shall understand by 'philosophical theism' the programme of gmng a 
dear coherent account of the nature of God (broadly consonant with 
what has been believed about him by Christian, Islamic and Jewish 
thinkers of tiic past two niillciiiiia^^ and ptovidLng cogciilaigumciits for 
the existence of such a God. 

Prcrvlding ar^mcnts - or^ more loose [y^ reasons - for the existence of 
God has been a concern of many theologians of the Christian tradition 
|[over the whole ot this period}. S\ V^uVs comment that 'the tnvLsibtc 
things' of God 'are clearly seen, being perceived through the things that 
are niadc'J gave Christian backing to the message of the middle chap- 
ters of the Old Testament TVLSffflm of Solomon that the existence and 
order of the Universe shows it to be the work oi a divine creator This 
Biblical tradition merged in the Hellenistic world with the arguments of 
Plato to th[> idea of the good and to tlic Dcmiuirge, atid with the argu- 
ments of Arlsloiile to the existence of the First Mover And so manv 
ClirLstlan theologians of the first millennium had their paragraph or two 
summarizing a cosmolo^cal argument or an argument from design. But 
it is normally only a paragraph or two,- and the reasoning is quick- My 
explanation of why they directed so little energ\^ to this issue is that they 
felt no need to do more. Most of their contemporaries accepted that 
thete was something like a god; what the thcotogians needed to argue 
for were tlie specially Chtlsttan doctrines about him- 

But in the medieval west theologians be^an to produce arguments 
for the existence of God at considerable length and with coi^tsiderable 
rigour; and they did their best lo give a coherent account of the nature 
of the God whose existence was purpottcdly demonstrated by these 



4 PhiiosGphy of Rifii^ion m itie 2istCi'}st\iry 

ai^monts- Tlic opening questions of St Thomas Aquinas's Smr^m^i 
T!ieoh^i{ie provide Lhc paradigm of medieval philosophical theism. The 
prc-K*intlan I^otcstant tradition also had a concern with this activity - 
more with arguments, Ihaii wiEh clarifying the divine nature^ and the 
arguments tended lo be less rigorous. The classical Protestants thought 
that while there were good argument for the existence of God, for rather 
more loosely^ Ihat nature showed clearly its creator) this w^as of little use 
to humans corrupted by siit.^ Lit>eral Proleslants, by contrast, argued at 
some len^h 'from nature up to Nature's God' and thought their argu- 
ments important. It was only with the arrival of Hume and Kant that 
some major parts of Che Cliristian tradition abandoned the pro|ect of 
natural theolog)'^ and they were in my view- ill-advised to do so. 

It needs to be emphasized that none of those thinkers in the first 
1750 years of Christiaiiity who thought that there arc good arguments 
fof the existence of God, thought that alJ or most believers ought to 
believe on the basis of those arguments, nor thai conversion required 
accepting those arguments as cogent.^ To be a Cliristian docs involve 
believing that there is a God, but most Christians may well have taken 
-God's existence for granted. Most converts may have belie\'ed bcfore- 
liand that there is a God; their conversion involved accepting more 
detailed claims about him. And if they did not initially believe that 
there is a God, ihey may have come to believe on the basis of religious 
experience in some sense rather than as the basis of natural theology. 
Nevertheless^ most Christian thinkefs before 17S0 held ihat there are 
these arguments availahlen and that those who do not initially believe 
thai there is a God and are rational can be brought Losee that there is a 
God by means of them.^ 

It is an interesting question why so much energy was put into the 
project of philosophical theology in the medieval west, when one might 
suppose that there was no more need of it than in earlier centuries - 
there were no rnore sophisticated atheists around^ one supposes. But the 
answer^ I susjx^ct, is ihat there is a bit of the sophisticated atheist in 
most believers^ and St Thomas and. Duns Scotus were providing tools 
to deal with that, however, as wc alJ know, atheism went public and 
expanded in the eighteenth century; until in out day in the West a 
large proportion of the population are atheists, and quire a lot of those 
who practise a theistie religion have serious doubts about whether there 
is a God- Yet the practices of the religion only have a point if there Ls a 
Ciod - there is no point in worshipping a non existent creator 6r asl^ing 
him to do something on Earth or take us to Heaven if he does i:tot 
exist; or trying lo hve our lives in accord with his will, If he has no will. 



If someone is to be rational in practising the Christian, Islamic or Jew- 
ish iciigionn he needs to believe (to some degree; the crcdal claims 
which undcrhc the practice. These claims include as their central 
clainij one presupposed by all the other claims, the claim that there is a 
God- If someone does not believe or only half -believes, the faithful are 
required (as part of Ihetr religious practice) to help. Help may take vari- 
ous forms. If wc can help someone to have a deep and cognitively 
compelling religious experience, let us do so; but religious expcfiences 
cannot be guaranteed, And the only way which requires the non- 
believer simply to exercise his existing faculties in the pursuit of some- 
thing which he is almost bound to regard as a good thing (to discover 
whether or not there Is a God), is to present him with arguments whose 
premises are things evident to the non-believer and whose principles of 
Inference are ones he accepts^ and to take him through them. And the 
oiily premises evident to ^ill non-beHe\'ers are the typical premises of 
rational iheolog)^ - the existence of the worlds its orderliness^ the exis- 
tence of human beings and so on. Tn our age. above all ages, theistie 
religion needs to have available natural theology. And since the rcasoits 
why people do not believe are not just the lack of positive grounds for 
believing^ but because they believe {or suspect) that there are internal 
incoherences in the concept of God, or that the existence of suffcrins 
disconfirms the existence of God, the believer needs to help them to 
see that this is not so. There are other means which might have success 
in our day - the need for philosophical theism is great - if in fact there 
is a God. 

But atheists are also interested in these questions, and they endeavour 
to show that there is no God; and since showing that an argument is 
not cogent or a concept is not coherent Involves the same techniques as 
the contrary endeavour, we may also call their activity ^philosophical 
tl:^eism^ Aaid if, in fact, thcrc is no God, it is good that some shall help 
others to a ri^ht ^iew of this matter, both for Its oww sake and also to 
save tliem from spending their time in pointless actlvity 

Such is the history and utility of philosophical theology How is it pur- 
sued today and what are its prospects? A lot of very thorough, detailed 
and rigorous work has been done with the aid of all the tools of analyti- 
cal philosophy in attempting to clarify what ^^ould he involved In there 
being a God, and atteinpting to show the claim tliat there is a God to be 
coherent or incoherent^ As regards positive arguments for the existence of 
God, different philosophers of today have revived different kinds of argu- 
ment from the past. Some have revived ontological argjments^ either 
producing variants of one or more classical arguments or producing 



6 Pfuiosophy of Ri^ii^ion m itie 2istCi'}stiiry 

some entirely new ontological argument. Omological arguments of 
course differ from all Lhc other traditional argumcnls Lii that they starts 
nor from something observable, but from purported logically necessary 
truths, [t is easy enough Co produce an onlological argument with ihe 
premises evident to all; and easy enough to produce a (deductively) valid 
ontologieal argimient. liul It is very hard indeed - iii my view quite 
impossible - to produce an ontological argument with both characleris- 
lies- It seems to me fairly evident that ihe proposition 'there is no God' 
while perli£ips false and even in some sense demonstrably false^ is not 
LncoherenL It does not contain any internal conlradLctton- And If that 
is so^ there could not be a valid ar^ment from logically necessary 
faiths to the existence of God. For 11: ihete were such an argument the 
existence of God would be logically necessary and its negation self- 
contradlccory- 

Then there is the tradition of attempting to produce deductiveiy 
valid arguments from prcmiici evident to the senses. It is a not unreason- 
able interprclatioii of Aquinas's 5wmfHf? Thivfosi^e L2.3- that he sought 
there to give five such arguments. TItose in our day who have sought to 
give such arguments have for the most part tried to do so with the aid 
of Thomist (or neo-Thomist> terminology. But the enterprise of produc- 
ing such arguments is also, I think, an enterprise doomed to failure. 
For if it could be achieved, then a proposition which was a conjunction 
of the evident premises together with "^thcrc Is no God' would be Inco- 
herent, would involve self-contradiction. But again propositions such 
as 'there is a Universe^ but there is no God\ though perhaps false and 
even in some sense dcmonstrahly false, seem fairly evidently coherent- 

So my own preference ts for the third tradition of natural theology. 
This begins from premises evident to the senses and claims that they 
make probable the existence of God. Such arguments purport to be 
Inductively cogent^ not deductively valid arguments. Arguinents of 
scientist; or historians from their data of observation to their general 
tlieorles or claims about the past or the future, also do not purport 
to be deductively valid^ merely inductively cogent. Thinkers were 
not very clear about the distinction between inductive and deductive 
arguments during the first one thousand years of the Christian era, 
and not much clearer until the eighteenth century. So it would be 
anachronistic to say that the patristic writers were seeking to give 
InductivCj or alternatively deductive arguments. But the arguments of 
so many British empiricists of the eighteenth century, culminating in 
Paley's Ni\tiin\i Theoio^, do seem to me fairly clearly and intentionally 
inductive. 



Rkfipni Swinbunje 7 

Arguments against the existence of God of all three kinds have also 
been produecd in our day^ but - i'or reasons of time - 1 shail concenliate 
on the positive. 

2 My own vetsl^ 

I model my own arguments for the existence of God on those of the 
third tradition, iiaeh of the various arguments from various observable 
phenomena does^ I argue^^ give some support to the claims that there 
is a God; and, taken to^etlicr^ they make It 'si^ificanii^- more probable 
than not'. 

1 have sought to show this with the aid of confirmation &>eory 
(that LEj the calculus of probability, used as a calculus for stating rela- 
tions of evidential support between propositions. 1 represent by P{p/q) 
the probability of a proposition p on evidence q- 1 use liayes^s Theorem, 

P(h;e&k>=P(e/h&k) ^^^, 

P(e/fc) 

to elucidate the relation between the probability of a hypothesis h on 
evidence of observation e and background knowledge k^ and other 
probabilities. To use this calculus does not involve supposinjij that exact 
values can very oftc:n be given to the probabilities involved. That exact 
values caiinot often be given is evident enough even when h is some 
paradigm scientific theory. It would be very odd to say that the proba- 
bility of Quantum Theory on the evidence of the photoelectric effect 
was U-'^2l7- Some probabilities can be given exact values - but this usu- 
ally happens only when the probability is 1, or 1/2. More often ^ all wc 
can say is that some probability has some rough value - more than this 
and less than that and that in consequence some other probability' has 
some other rough value - close to U or fairly high or less tlian ihai. My 
cbricem has been to prove that svhcn e is a conjunctiori oT propositions 
which set out the publicly available evidence which has been used in 
arguments for and against the existence of God, and k is tautological 
background evidence (viz. contains nothing relevant to h) and h Is the 
existence of God, P(h/e^k) is 'significantly greater titan 1/2'. 

All thai the calculus does Ls to set out in a rigorous formal way the fac- 
tors which determine how observational evidence stipports more general 
theory. The rclevaiit points can be made easily enough in words^ but less 
rigorously and with tlieir implications less clear. \Miat the calculus 
brings out is that a general theory h is rendered probable by obser^'a- 
tlonal evidence e ( and if we put k as a tautolog\^ we can now ignore 



B PhiiosGphy of Ri^ii^ion m itie 21st Ci'}!tury 

it)^ insofar as (1) P(e/h&k) (the posterior probability of c J is high, (2) 

P(h/kJ (the prior probabilSty of h) is high^ and (S) P(c/k) (the prior 
probability of c) is low. The first condition Is satisfied to the extent to 
ivhicli you would expect to find e if h is true- Obviously a scientifie or 
historical theorj^ is rendered probable, insofar as the e^rjdencc Ls such as 
you would expect to find if the theory is true. (1 can say "'the theory is 
rendered probable insofar as it yields true predictions' but only if it is 
understood that the 'predictions' may be evidence observed cither 
before or after the theory was formulated. It seems irrelevant lo 
whether evidence supports a theory whether it is 'iiew' evidence found 
by testing a theory^ or 'old' evidence which the new tlieory explains.") 

However^ for any e you can dcvtsc an infinite number of different 
incompatible theories h whicli are such tliat for each P(e/h&k> is high 
but which make totally different predictions from each olher for the 
future (that is, predictions additional to e). Let c be ail tlie observations 
made relev'ant to your favourite theory of mechanics - let's say General 
Relativity (GTR). Then you can complicate GTR in innumerable ways 
such that the resulting new theories all predict e but maite wildly diffe- 
rent predictions about what will happen tomorrow. The jjrounds for 
believing that GTR is the true theory is chat GTR is the simplest theory. 
P(h/k) means the a priori probability that h is true, or - put less 
challengingly - is the measure of the strength of the a priori factors 
relevant to the probability of h. The major such a priori factor is sim- 
plicity. The simplicity of a theory is something internal to that theory^ 
not a matter of the relation of the theory to external evidence. Another 
a priori factor is content - the bigger a theory, the more and more pre- 
cise claims it makes, the less likely it is to be true. But we can ignore 
this factor if we are comparing theories of similar content. 

P(e/k) is a measure of how likely e is to occur if we do not assume any 
particular theory to be true. The iiormai effect of this term in assessing 
the probability' of any particular theory h^ is that e does not render h very 
probable if you would expect to find e anyw^ay [for example^ if it was also 
predicted by the main rivals to h which had signifieant prior probability). 

for the purpose of applying this apparatus to assessing the theory 
that there is a God, the philosophical theist needs to spell out what is 
meant by tliis claim. God is supposed to be roughly a person without a 
body, essentially omnipotent, omniscient, perfectly free, perfectly good, 
creator and suslaincr of any universe there may be, a source of moral 
obligation, eternal and necessary.^ It needs to be spelled out what each 
of these properties amounts to, and to be shown that possession of 
each is compatible with possession of the others. Inevitably^ to talk of 
the source of all being involves using words in somewhat stictched 



senses - just as^ in a humbler way^ doc5 talk about photons and pto- 
tons. liut it needs to he tnadc to some extent clear just what the 
stretching amounts to in each case, and to be made plausible that when 
ivords arc used in the stretched sense^ the claims about God made with 
their aid are coherent. It's no good saving 'aJl our talk about God is 
metaphorical'. For [f anyone is even to have a belief that there is a God, 
let alone have grounds for that l>clicf^ there must be some difference 
betw-een that belief and the belief that there is no God, or the l>cliel" that 
there is a Great Pumpkin^ or whatever And to explain to a non-believer 
what that belief is, one must use words which she understands. 
That involves inakiii^ it clear when words are being used in stretched 
senses and - insotar as it can be done - what are the boundaries of 
these senses. The claim that there is a God may of course not be a 
fully clear claim, but unless II is moderately clear, it cannot provide 
backing for the practice of religion nor can arguments be given for or 
against it. 

I argue that any being who is essentially omnipotent, omniscient, and 
perfectly free, and cvcrlasliiig necessarily has the other divine properties^ 
and that the cited properties fit together in a very Jieat way so that the 
claim that there is a God is a very simple claim^ because it is a claim for 
the existence of the simplest kind of person there could be, Persons are 
beings with power to bring about effects intentionally, beliefs ^true or 
false) about how things are, and some degree of freedom to exercise 
thetr power God is postulated as a being with zero limits to his pow^ern 
to his true beliefs^ and to his freedom. Scientists and others always pre- 
fer on grounds of sunplicity hypotheses which postulate one entity 
rather than manyn and entities with zero or infinite degrees of their 
properties rather than some finite degree thereof. They postulate that 
photons have zero mass (rattier tiian some very small mass, equally 
compatible with obsetvations); and they used to postulate liiaL light 
and the gravitational force travel with infinite velocity [rather than 
sonic very large finite velocity, equally compatible irVitli observations; 
until observations forced a differeiil theory' on them. Although the exis- 
tence of anything at all Is perhaps enormously improbable a priori, the 
existence of a very simple being lias a far higher prior probabLlit}^ than 
does the existence of anything else (except insofar as the latter is ren- 
dered probable by the former), 

Yci Lf there i^ a Ciod^ it is not improbable that he should create a uni- 
verse, an orderly universe, and within it embodied rational creatures such 
as huniaiis- For God Ix^ing good will seek to bring about good things. It is 
good that there should be a beautiful universe, lieautj' arises from order 
of some kind - the orderly interactions and movcmenli of objects in 



accord with natural lairvs is beautiful indeed; and even more beautiful 
are ihc plants and animals which evolved on Earth. It is a further good 
that ihere should be human beln^ who can eboose between good and 
bad, choose whether to grow in power and knowledge, and %o choose 
ivhclher or not to enter into a loving relationship with God himself. 
Humans have limited power over their bodies :ind acquire naturally 
some knowledge of how the world worts. Wc have to know which bod- 
ily movements will make what difference - and thai involves Ihere 
being regularities in the worM which we can grasp. The movements of 
solid bodies in empty space follow (apptoximaicly) S'ewion's laws. 
Given such simple rc^laritics, we can discern them and use them to 
increase our power over the universe - to develop our agriculture, to 
make houses and bridges^ to send humans to the moon. So God lias a 
futthet reason to create a universe orderly in Its conformity to rational 
laws - in giving huanajis significant choices which affect themselves, 
each other and their relation to God. 

But unless there is a God, it is most unlikelv that there would bt a 
universe at alL The jniversc is a big thing consisting of very many sepa- 
rate objects of varying finite size and mass. That it should exist on its 
own, uncreated- is therefore - bv normal scientific criteria - verv much 
less Wkdy than that God should exist. And it Is most unlikely that the 
Universe would come into existence caused by anything else than God^ 
because any other possible cause is much less simple than God. And it 
is immensely unlikely that if there is a Universe^ it should be governed 
by simple natural laws. For natural laws are not entities- To say that all 
objects obey Newton^s laws is just to say that each obj^^ct in the 
Universe behaves in a way that Newton's taws state, that is^ has exactly 
the same properties of movement in reaction to the presence of other 
objects^ as does every other object- It is immensely unlikely that every 
otiicr object should behave In exactly the same way - a priori, unless 
there was a common cause of their having ttie properties they do. And 
any other possible cause is much less simple than God. (Even it" you 
suppose some impersonal cause to be just as simple a postulate as God, 
there is no reason why it should bring about this sort of universe.} 

$o the h^'pothesis of theism satisfies the three criteria which I have 
drawn from D ay cs's Theorem and arc independently plausihlen for the 
probability of a theory_ The only evidence which I have mentioned is 
that of the existence of the .Universe and its 'conformity to natural 
laws'. Tn my books I have also adduced much further evidence- the ini- 
tial slate of the Universe being such and the laws having such character- 
istics as to bring" about somewhere in the Unlveise animals and humans 



Ricfmni Swinbunnf 1 1 

(the ^fine-tuning' of the Universe}; the cjcistcnce of consciousness^ 
vaiious providcmml aspects of nature^ the public evidence about the 
lifCf death and purported resurrection of Jesus of Nazareth, other 
reports of niiraclcSn and the very widespread phenomenon of ■" religious 
experiences', in ihc sense of experiences vvliich seem lo their subjects 
to he expcrLcncK of God_ The case for the existence of God wliich I 
have just iuminarized is a ajmulative one from many pieces of evi- 
dence. Arguments against the existence of God (for otamplen from evil) 
have also to be brought into the equation^ and it needs to be shown 
that the hypothesis of theism rcLains its probabilily despite thcsc. 



3 Objt<:tii>ns 

What of objections? Ever since people have given arguments for the 
exisiencc of God, others have uied to find fallacies In them. There are 
innumerable objections l>otli to tlie general programme and to particu- 
lar versions of it. 1 confine myself lo objections to the arguments for the 
cL^tni that there is God, and - for reasons of time - shall not consider 
objcetions to the colictcnce of that claim. I begin with objections to the 
geneial programme. 

Fiistn there is the objccUon that if arguments for the existence of God 
(and certain claims about wliat he has done) are cogent^ then a prudent 
person will try to do what is good out of self-interest - for (probal^lyj 
God will approve such behaviour and reward it. The total eommitmcnt 
demanded by religious faith would no longer be virtuous- Kierkegaard 
wrote that the suggestion that faith might be replaced by 'probabilities 
and guarantees' is for the believer 'a temptation to be resisted with all 
liis strength\^ Of course religion involves commitment^ that is, living 
by Lhe assumpiion that tlic relevant religious system is true- But tl:icre 
is always risk in a commitment to an assumption which may be false - 
you may spend your life pursuing good Ltiin^ which you will never 
attain, and lose good things which you could have attained- Yet if the 
former good things are good enough - and plausibly the licatitic Vision 
of God in the company ot the saints for yourself and your fellows fas 
Avetl as many earthly good thingsj is good enough, it is a risk worth 
taking. The prudence of seeking such a ^ood, despite risk of failure, is 
virluous- And if it is probable ^though not certain) Lhat there Ls a God, 
it is probable that you have a duty to commit yourself to God. But 
there is nothing virtuous in living your life on an assumption which is 
certainly false - for that is pointless. Given that there is some risk that 



12 Phih.wphy (yfRdi^iois in f/re 21ii Century 

there is no God likely to reward yov, as the third tradition of ar^nient 
allows^ this criticism fails. 

Then there Is Kierkegaard's ob]ectioii from the opposite angle, direeted 
at I he third tradition of argument, that it would leave us with an uncer- 
tain beltet open to revision - and lliat religion requires raore.^ I do not 
ihink that rcli;^ion does require more - by way of belief. St Paul 
reminded us tliat Ve see in a mirror darkly^ but then face lo face: now 
I know in pari; buL then siialf I know even as also I have been known/^"^ 
and that ^by hope were we saved: but hope that Is seen is not hope: for 
who hopcth for that which he seelh?'^' Religion requires more than 
tentative commitment^ but there is no diffieulty in giving that com- 
mitment to a system which is only probably true. 

Then there is the objection that arguments for the existence of God, 
especially ones which involve probabilities, are sophisticated things; 
and only iiitellcctuais can understand them. Even if this were true, it is 
no good objection to the project - intellectuals need their views on reli- 
gion by which to live as much as does anyone else; and if their need 
alone can be satisfied, that is something. But in fact 1 suj^gest that almost 
all traditional arguments for lite existence of God (apart from the onto- 
logical argument) codify in a more rigorous form the vague feeling of so 
many humans that the existence of the world with its various particular 
features cries out for an explanation^ and thai God^s action in creating 
and sustaining it provides that explanation. That feeling is then open 
to various atheistic objections which can be dealt with in turn by more 
rigorous formulation ai:td defence. 

Then tiiere is the LEarthian objection that philosophical thciiim has 
too anthropomorphic a view of God. liut the Christian view of God is 
in ctuciai respects anthropomorphic. It is central lo the Christian tradi- 
tion (as to the Jewish and Islamic traditions) that God ^created man in 
his own image',^- and the very many theologians of the tw^o Christian 
millennia who have dwelt on these words have seen the ^image^ as pri- 
marily a matter of rationality and free will (and so of power and knowl- 
edgeX that is^ properties contingently present in humans in a small 
degree which are necessarily present in God in an inrinite degree. God 
is like man because man is like God. if we are to be concerned with 
arguments for the existence of the God of Christianity^ w-c must - with 
all the qualifications about stretched language mentioned earlier - be 
anthropomorphic about God. 

There are many other general objections to the programme of philo- 
sophical theism - I findn for example^ t^lgbt separate ones^ in Hume's 
Dialogues. But my view is that most such objections derive any force 



Ricfitini Swinbuniif 13 

that the^' may have fiom a positivism now largely rejected in philosophy 

generally (aiidj in parllcular, in philosophy of science)- Tticre is, for 
example, the view that causation concerns patterns of regularity in 
obiservahlc objects, and ihere is no sense hi lalLing of ihe unobscfvahle 
cause of a unique ohjcct. Eul while no object (even God) is unique in 
all respects, all objects arc unique in some respects; and science is 
findinj^ out rather a lot about the unobscrvable causes of the obscrv- 
able. I think that there is little force in any of these general objections 
to the programme of philosophical theism. Wliat 1 believe to be much 
more Important are detailed objections designed to shoiv that some 
particular theistic claim is incoherent^ or that all available versions of 
tlietstic arguments do not work. It" 1 am right in my ciaim that the 
probability calculus captures the prLnclpies of inductive inference in a 
precise form, then If someone can find a fault in my version of the pro- 
gramme, that wtll suffice to render the whole programme worthless. 

There arc objeaions to each of my claims about the three elements on 
the right hand side of Eayes's Theorem, when this is applied to assessing 
tlie probabilily of the existence of God (hj on the evidence of observa- 
tion (e) and tautoloj^eal background evidence fk). Rrst, the objector 
claims that P(c/h & k) is very low indeed^ because of the problem of cvil^ 
including pain and other suffering, which is vcEy - if not totally - 
improbable if there is a God. In my view the problem of evil consti- 
tutes the most substantial of all objections to tlie existence of God. But 
even to begin to meet it, my paper would need to deal solely w^ith it. So 
all that I have space to do here is to say that some evils are necessary 
conditions of greater goods- It is not improbable lliat God will bestow 
on some creatures not merely the ^ood of pleasure; but the goods of a 
free choice of good or evil u^hleli makes a significaait difference to tlic 
worlds the opportunity to show patience, courage and compassion, and 
tlie privilege of making it possible (by our suffering) for oLhcrs to evince 
these virtues, and much else. T claim that God (logically') cannot pro- 
vide us with these good things without causing or allowing suffering, 
and that it would not be wrong of him to cause or allow the suffering 
for a limited period in a limited way for the sake of the goods which it 
makes possible. But to show this at adequate length requires a very 
substantial theodicy, for which 1 can only put dow^n a markcrJ* 

Then, the objector claims that Pfh/k) is low^ because the hypothesis 
of theism is not nearly as simple as 1 suggest, and the hypothesis makes 
such big claims (its content is so laTg:el- 1 do think that this is a very 
substantial objection^ allhou;jh in the end mistaken. The content of 
any hypothesis able to explain the existence of the Universe will have 



14 Phihwpby iyfRtli^iGU Pf? the 21.'ht Century 



to be pfotty large. The hypothesis of theism postulates one God of infi- 
nite powcr^ knowledge and so on, rather than one or many finite ones- In 
the course of a very Interesting paper Mark Wynn has pointed out (hat 
there are very many diftereitt possible hypotheses^ eaeh postulating dif- 
ferent numbers ol" gods wiili different powers, whereas there is only one 
hypothesis poslutatin^ one God of infinite power, flcnce, he claims, 
although each of the former hypotheses mi^ht be less probahle a priori 
than ihe hypothesis of theisnin the disjunction of the former is plausibly 
more probable than the hypothesis of theismJ"^ liut if the order of the 
world is to be explained by many gods, then some explanation Is 
required for how and why they cooperate Lii producing the same pat-^ 
terns ot order throughout the Universe. This becomes a new datum 
requiring explanation for the same reason as the fact of order itself. The 
need for further explanation ends when we postulate one l>elng who is 
the cause of the existence of all otliers^ and the simplest conceivable 
such - J urge - is God. 

Finally there is the objection that we can pass no judgement on thf^ 
value of P(c/k). WhaL possible factots couid lead us to a view about 
how likely it would be that there w^ould be a universe, whether or not 
there is a God? Bui that is easy enouj^h to answer. The probability of e 
is the sum of probabilities of the different ways in which c can come 
about^ that iSj the sum of the probabilities of c on each fival hypothe- 
sis, multiplied by the prior probability of that rival hypothesis. P(c/k] = 
P(e/h&k) I\h/k)-hP(e/ht&k) P(hi/k) + P^e/h2£:k) P^h2/k}... and so on. 
By earlier arguments, all hypotheses of similar content which lead us to 
expect e arc much less simple than h. h] and the others are such that 
P{h!/k)«P{h/k) Hence P(e/k) is not too much larger than Pfe/h&k) 
Pth/k). When we pass judgemeni on the probability of any scientific 
theory for which there is no greatly relevant contingent background 
evldciicc k, wc pass just this sort of judgement. 

4 Rival pro^i^rainmes 

How has the programme of philosophical theism engaged with other 
programmes represented at this conference? Ey far the closest prog- 
ramme is that of keformed Episiemology. Jitdeed, 1 do not regard it as a 
separate programme, but rather as one end ot a spectrum, of which phLto 
sophicai theism is the other end of a spectrum of programmes defending 
the rationality of belief in a liraditional Christian God (on a uhTvocal 
understaiidin^ of 'rationality. The canonical presentation of Reformed 
EpLstemology is the volume edited by Plantiitga and Woherstorff, Fuith 



Rictitini Swinbuniif \S 

{\!id R{itior^aiity.^^ These writers, and all who have followed them, have 
used all the tools of inodcrn aiirLlytic philosophy, as have I and many 
others who have tried to develop philosophical theism. 'IVhal is central 
to Reformed Epislemology is the claim Lhat ihe belief thai there is a God 
can be entirely rational without being feased on arguments from evh 
dence; it may bo 'properly basic^ the sort of belief which, like mundane 
perceptual beliefs such as 1 sec a dcsk'j Is ralionaHy believed without being 
based on oiher beliefs. I agree with thaL - behef lhat there is a God can 
be, for some people^ properly basic. And almost all philosophical the> 
ologlans of the past i\^o millennia would think that loo. So long as it 
stares you in the face that some belief is true and you have no contrary 
evidence^ then that belief is pmperly basic^ and if anyone today is in 
that position witli regard to their belief that there is a God^ that belief iSj 
for them properly basic. Bat one difference between myself and many 
Reformed Epistemoloj;jists is that in n:Ly view the number of people in 
the western world in Lbis situation tn 1999 is fairly small. Most people 
today need something by way of positive argument for then thefstk 
belief to be rational. But this difference concerns merely the utility of 
the programme of Reformed Epistemologyn not the truth of its doctrines, 
Some Reformed lipistemolo^sts however seem to be saying that there 
arc no good arguments for the existence of God - and there of course I 
disagree for reasons given earlier in this paper- Sometimes also they seem 
to be mo\rcng towards the claim that it is not rational to believe in God 
on the basis of arguments; and of course here too 1 disagree. 

Until 1986, the main clatm of Reformed Epistemology was simply the 
negative claim that the claim of others that 'there is no God' is not prop- 
erly basic for anyone who had no good justification. Since then Plantinga 
has dev'cloped his theory of warrant, warrant being whatever it is that 
turns true belief into knowledge J^ According to this theorj' a belief B is 
warranted if it satisfies a number of conditions, the crucial one of which 
is that ^the cognitive faculties involved in the production of B are func- 
tioning properlyV^ *Lnd that means functioning the way your creator 
intended them to function (if you have a creator)^ or (if you do not liave 
a creator) functioning the way evolution in some seasc Intended' you to 
function. The application of Plantinga's theory of w^arrant to religious 
belief has the consequences that if ihcre is a God, it is probable thai 
a belief that there is a God is warranted- and if tliere is no God, it is 
probable thai a belief that there is a God is not warranted. Even if this 
conclusion Is corfect, it is of httle use to us, unless wq have reason to 
believe that there is (or is not) a God, and that involves having a belief 
about the issue which is rational in a different sense from Plantin^a's 



16 Phih^optiy (yfRdi^iois in tfi^ 21ii Century 

'warranted'. In this alternative sense our beliefs are rational If they are 

probable on the evidence available to us (which will include ihe appar- 
■?nt dclivcranecs of religious experience, as well as publicly available evi- 
dence}- The probabiliLy involved here is the logical or cpislcniic kind 
with which T was operating earlier. The rationality of his or her beliefs 
in this sense is sometiilri;^ internally accessible to the subject and uo a 
considerable degree) to everyone else as well. A reformed epistemolo- 
gist needs to hold tliat theistic beliefs afe rational in this sense, if he is 
to justify his claim (to himself and the world) that they are probably 
true. 1 hope tl^al Reformed Episleniolo^, all of whose tools and many 
of whose results 1 endorse^ will recognize the need for this strong inter- 
nalist kind of rationality and not saddle itself with an exclusively exter- 
nalist epistemology. 

flow does Philosophical Tlielsm inieraet with Wittgeitstcin? 
Wittgenstein is of course one of the great philosophers of all time, recog-^ 
nized as such by both the analytic and continental traditions of philos- 
ophy. Any philosopher must take account of Wittgenstein; and I like to 
think that I have learnt a little from htm and applied it to one or two par- 
ticular issues. As we know, he wrote very little directly about reli^on, and 
his main influence on the philosophy of religion has been through the 
application by others (and especially D.Z. Phillips) of what he %vrotc 
about language In developing those few explicit remarks about religion. 
The resulting position has often l>cen called 'Wittgenstein! an fidcism'. 
Now the way in which I, or indeed most analytical philosophers, 
approach some writer is to try to analyse what they have written in 
terms of a few philosophical claims and various supporlin^ ar^ments; 
and then to attack or defend these claims by further arguments. To 
approach any VVittgcnstcinian in this way can be a frusti'ating experience. 
One is told that one's account of the philosophical claims Is far too naive^ 
and that to produce head-on arguments for or against such claims is a 
naive way to deal with them. One is finalEy left with the Impression that 
one can only understand what the writer is saying If one endorses It. 

My account of what D.Z. Phillips has been claiming over many years 
in fidelity to Wittgenstein's few explicit remarks on the subject, Is that 
religion Is a self-contained practice Cof prayer, worship, public and 
private conduct, and the way we think about thin^sj^ comtnitmenL to 
which involves no metaphysical or historical beliefs different from those 
of people who do not practise llie religion. As an account of the Christian 
reli^on, as it has been practised by so many over two millennia, this 
seems manifestly false. Of course there have been a few sophisticated 
modern people who have gone through the motions of prayer and 
worshipj and taken Christian stances on particular moral IssueSj without 



16 Phih^optiy (yfRdi^iois in tfi^ 21ii Century 

'warranted'. In this alternative sense our beliefs are rational If they are 

probable on the evidence available to us (which will include ihe appar- 
■?nt dclivcranecs of religious experience, as well as publicly available evi- 
dence}- The probabiliLy involved here is the logical or cpislcniic kind 
with which T was operating earlier. The rationality of his or her beliefs 
in this sense is sometiilri;^ internally accessible to the subject and uo a 
considerable degree) to everyone else as well. A reformed epistemolo- 
gist needs to hold tliat theistic beliefs afe rational in this sense, if he is 
to justify his claim (to himself and the world) that they are probably 
true. 1 hope tl^al Reformed Episleniolo^, all of whose tools and many 
of whose results 1 endorse^ will recognize the need for this strong inter- 
nalist kind of rationality and not saddle itself with an exclusively exter- 
nalist epistemology. 

flow does Philosophical Tlielsm inieraet with Wittgeitstcin? 
Wittgenstein is of course one of the great philosophers of all time, recog-^ 
nized as such by both the analytic and continental traditions of philos- 
ophy. Any philosopher must take account of Wittgenstein; and I like to 
think that I have learnt a little from htm and applied it to one or two par- 
ticular issues. As we know, he wrote very little directly about reli^on, and 
his main influence on the philosophy of religion has been through the 
application by others (and especially D.Z. Phillips) of what he %vrotc 
about language In developing those few explicit remarks about religion. 
The resulting position has often l>cen called 'Wittgenstein! an fidcism'. 
Now the way in which I, or indeed most analytical philosophers, 
approach some writer is to try to analyse what they have written in 
terms of a few philosophical claims and various supporlin^ ar^ments; 
and then to attack or defend these claims by further arguments. To 
approach any VVittgcnstcinian in this way can be a frusti'ating experience. 
One is told that one's account of the philosophical claims Is far too naive^ 
and that to produce head-on arguments for or against such claims is a 
naive way to deal with them. One is finalEy left with the Impression that 
one can only understand what the writer is saying If one endorses It. 

My account of what D.Z. Phillips has been claiming over many years 
in fidelity to Wittgenstein's few explicit remarks on the subject, Is that 
religion Is a self-contained practice Cof prayer, worship, public and 
private conduct, and the way we think about thin^sj^ comtnitmenL to 
which involves no metaphysical or historical beliefs different from those 
of people who do not practise llie religion. As an account of the Christian 
reli^on, as it has been practised by so many over two millennia, this 
seems manifestly false. Of course there have been a few sophisticated 
modern people who have gone through the motions of prayer and 
worshipj and taken Christian stances on particular moral IssueSj without 



Ricfitini Swinbuniif 17 

having any specifically Christian historical or metaphorical hclicfs. 

Some have even used the traditional language - for example^ 'Last Judge- 
men T - in some waj^ utterly different from the ways of the normal 
Christian. liut lo understand Christiamty^ ifs no good rcadinj; only 
Simonc Weil - you need to read St Paul, IrenaeuSn and Gregory of Nyssa 
and Luther and Francis dc Sales and so on, and so on_ WiUgen stein ian 
philosoptiy of rdigion suffers from a very one-sided diet of examples. 
I know that there are differences between the writers I nientionn but 
they are as nothinj^ compared with ihe difference between them and, 
say, Don Cupitt. But having written this, 1 know that 1 shall be accused 
of failing to understand the subtleties of lan;^age and religion; and 
I await the accusation with due trepidation. 

Then we come to Process Thought. I have always found the few writ- 
ings of Process tli Inkers which 1 have read ^despite the complexities of 
Whitehead's metaphysics), relatively dear But they expound a meta- 
ph)^ic which seems to me a lot less probable than a more uaditional 
Christian one. The attempt by Process Thought to dispense with the 
category of substance seems to mc to fail, in particular lit its account of 
persons. A subsequent person betn^ me is not a matter of its causal rela- 
tions or relations of similarity to earlier events. Many different series of 
subsequent events could have very close such relations to tlie earlier 
events which svere mine. Yet - with immense plausibility - there would 
be a truth about which series of subsequent events were mine. Being me 
can^ in consequence, only be analysed as being the same continuing 
substance (that is^ soul). The category of substance is unavoidable; and 
one everlasting 5u[>stance on which all depends is required Lo make 
sense of the world. While in this way, like all philosophical thcistSn 
I object Lo h'ocess Theolo^'s conceptual scheme; unlike some philo- 
sophical theistSn ] accept from Process Theology certain more particular 
view^s about God. God is not outside time; and God docs not know 
infallibly the future free choices of creatures. 

And finally what of Post- Modernism and Critical Theory? I am alas 
too ignorant of critical theory to have engaged with it. In philosophy 
generally I think of post-Modemism as the view that there is no truth, 
there are just sentences expressed In different circumstances to which 
people react in different ways and then utter more sentences^ and I find 
this \1cw in the little I have read of Dcrrida. As I have read so little of 
the Continental philosophy from which post-Niodcrnism emerged^ like 
so many other analytic philosophcrSn what I have jusf written may l>e a 
poor caricature; and^ if so^ I apologize - I am here to learn better.. 

But if post-Mode niism is the view which I have stated, it seems to me 
manifestly false, l^or how couid it be a vicw^ a. belief about how things 



L8 Phih.wptiy (yfRdi^iois in tlj^ 21ii Cei^tury 

arCn unless cilhcr it Is true or il is false? And in that case there Is truth - 
cither the truth of post-Modernism, or the truth thai post-Modernism is 
false. If the former, then post-Modemism contradicts Itself; and hence 
only the lalter Is possible. Now maybe post-Modernism is a bit subtler 
than 1 have rGpresented It. Maybe ii claims that tlierc are some truths 
but not many. But it seems lo me far more obvious than most things, 
that a lot of modern science is true, that tlic world is very old, that there 
are people beside myself and so on. These ihings are far more obvious 
than any philosophical doctrine. We have an enonnous nLimbcr of true 
beliefs. Posi-Modernism may be warning us that different groups have 
different criteria of rationality and that there is not one true set of crite- 
ria. Although there are small diffeteiices between groups as to ivhat they 
take as evidence for what^ T do not myself believe that those differences 
ihcre arc greatly significant; humans have very similar criteria to each 
other. This is a contingent claim and I could Ix^ wrong. But if I am 
ivrong, that does not damage my claim that there is one true set of criie- 
ria. They are those of my group, which - 1 am quite sure - arc those of all 
who will hear or read ibis pajKr. We all have the modern scientific crite- 
ria of what ts evidence for what, and to say that we have these criteria is 
just to say that we believe that the results which they yield about what is 
probable to be correct results, [f we thought that there are no true crite- 
ria of what is evidence tor what, we would think it just as likely that If 
we jump froni a window we will fl% as that we will fall to the ground. 
Our conduct shows that we do not so think One can however take a 
post-Modernist view about religion without becoming susceptible to the 
difficulties of a more general post-Modernism. One can claim that there 
are no icligtous truths (l>ccausc religious claims are incoherent), or tliat - 
if there are - it is equally rational to hold any religious belief. The answer 
to this more detailed claim (itself presumably purportedly true and 
assei'led as ralionaL) Is the detailed programme of philosophical theism 
sketched earlier. Detailed challenges to ttie coherence of traditional the- 
ism can Ix^ met, and it can be shown probable^ and so more rational lo 
believe than its negation^ by correct criteria of rationality. 



Notts 

L Epistle to the Romans l.m 

Z. For a iilghlly longer form of argument iivm design tbr the existence oJ' God^ 

and arguiTient thereffom ^bout the nature of God^ jfe theoi?ening chapters of 

St John of Damascus, Exp^^.iition t?fihe Gittro^oM Faith. 



Rictitini Swinbunnf 19 

3. 5W John Calvin^ Initilutes of theChiisEian Religion^ Book l^ ch_ 5_ 

4. Cx>iivers3on of course involves not mere5y coming to believe ceitain propo- 
sitions, but netting yourself To act on them in certain wav^- l^ut my concern 
here is only witl^ the former necessary Isut not suffEcient element in conver- 
sion. Hence I ^-iTlie of the person who does practise a rehgion as 'ttie 
believer' and the one who dr^es not a=^ 'the non -believer'. 

5. 'Not that the same method of instructics]i will be suitable in the case of all 
who approach the Word... tlie method oJ r^jcovery must be adapted to the 
form of the disease ___ pi] is necessary to regard the opinions which the per- 
sons have taiien up, and so frame your aigumeni in accordance with the 
error into ^viiich eacli have fa3[enr by advancing in each discussion certain 
principles and reasonable propositions, that thus^ through \vhat is agreed 
on both sides^ the tnjth may conclusively be brought to light. Should fyour 
d|)ipDnents] say there is no God^ then^ from the consideration of the skilful 
and wise economy of the Universe he will tyi brought to acknowledge that 
there is a certain overmastering power manifested throuj^^h these channels/ - 
St Gregory of Nyssa, The Great Catechism^ Prologue (trans. W_ N/foore and H.A. 
Wilson, tn Selected Wnti^ig.'i ofGre^o^y ofJ^y^a, Parker and Co., Oxford, lS9;i^. 

6. 5e^ my E:xistcfitrc of Goti, Clarendon Prei^^. revised edilion^ 1990 land the 
short simplBhed version, Is There ii G^kf^^ Oxford University Press^ 1996). 

7. In the Christian tradition Cod is 'three persons in one substance' - that is. 
three p^irsons ^ach of whom has the lifted divine characteristics - the Son 
and the Spirit being eternany and necessarily caused to e_xi:^t by tlie Father. 
Argurnent^ to the existence of Cod are then best construed as argLiments to 
the existence of God the Father, from which the existence of Son and Spirit 
follow - in my view by logical entailment. Ilie simp3icity of God which 
I consider in the text is the simplicity of God the FaCl^er - that a simple 
theory 3ias complicated consequences does not make it any less simple. 
T ignore this complication in subsequent discussion^ for the sake of ease 
of exiH>sition_ Tor my own developed account of the divine nature see TIst 
Coht^re}ice ofTtieh^n, CJarendon Press, revised editions^ 1993: and The Chnr^l- 
itni Goti^ Clarendon Press^ 1594. 

a. S. Kierkejaaid. C{tffchii-fing Un.'ieieutific F^yst^crfpt {trans. H. V. and EM. j-iongj^ 
[*ilnceion University Press^ 1992, p. IL 

9. Tor reference to this objection of Kierkegaard both to uatural theology and to 
historical arguments about the life and teaching of Jesus, and for a developed 
response both to this objection and to the previous Kierkegaardian objection^ 
5*^^ Robert M. Adams, 'Kierkegaard's Arguments against Ohjectlv^: Reasoning 
Jn I^JEgLon', in his The Viniie of faith, Oxford University Press^ t9S7_ 
10- I Corinthians 13-12- 

11_ Romans R.24_ 

12- Genesis 1.Z7.-.. 

L3- I devoted two and half chapters o^ Tiie Ejiisttnct of Gad to theodicy (pp. 
1S2-60 and chs- 10 and 11). but feeling the need for more extensive treat- 
nientj have noiv written a full-length book on this - Pnfvideric*: {;nd the Frob- 

tetuofEvii, Clarendon Pte^s, 199B_ 
14- "Mark Wynn. 'Some Reflections on Richard Swinburne's Argument from 
Design'^ R^h^ioiis Smiiies 29 il99ipj,, 1^25-35- Wynn points out that I need to 



20 Phih^ophy (yfRdi^iois in f/re 21ii Century 

make this kind of Twovt in a different connection in order to defeat an 
earlit^r objection of Mackic. 

15. A_ Plantinga and N_ "Wolterstorff, Ffiith ami Rcithmuhiy^ Univeisiiy of Notre 
Danrie Press^ \9SA 

16. 5d^ rlanEinga's generaS ttieory of episrenioSog/ in Vl^^^iurnnrr the Current Debate 
and lVrtmi?;f i^nJ Fwpi^r Fimctiim^ Oxford Universit/ PresSr 199;i; and itsappli- 
cations to t^hiiitian belief, in WiUJtmte^i Chmthm Beiief, Oxford University 

Press, 2CKH>. 
L7. IVcrrrff/iC fj/arf Propter fiifictior^^ p. 194_ 



18 

Voices in Discussion 



U: In the firs! iliroe symposia wc heard a lot about the relation between 
rcligtotis expcricncG and reason, I doubt whether wg can generalize 
about this, I was brought up in a pious Southern MctliodisL home in 
Japan. I was socialized iiito Cliristianlty. Wy world was theocentrtc_ 
While in the army 1 not only had ordinary religiou-S expcricnccSj but 
also some dramatic ones. One of the latter was a call to be a minister. 
I thoughtj however^ that I ought to study objections to ChrisLianity 
l>efore answering it. Most of the people I had met in the army were 
Roman Catholics^ as different from Southern Methodists as one could 
imagine« 

In the university I studied models of analysis of ideas and methods. I 
was taught by Richard McKcon, who never accepted what any student 
said- 1 kept as quiet as I could- McKeon taught the history of philoso- 
phy. He put the patterns of thought of the different philosophers on 
the blackboard. What emerged was a pluralist history. There was no 
question of truth and falsity^ but only of which pattern was most 
appropriate for our day. Each system w^as sclf<ontaiiiedj, as though this 
were a basic way of organizing thought. 

I now Lhink more in historical terms. I believe that the w-ay the mind 
works is determined by the questions people ask. The mind cannot 
generate a universal^ right [ihjiosophy. This reflects my attitude to what 
philosophy can and cannot do. Some claim to he arguing from a neutral 
position. 1 am not con\1nced. It is an Olympian height only within that 
s\^stcm, rhilosnphy caiinot tdi theology what to think or vice versa. 

I found objections to Christianity in modern thought. But it wasn't 
so much that I found good arguments and assessed evidence, hut that I 
found that my formci faith simply was not there. It wasn't a matter of 
choice. I could remember my former experiences, but they now made 



2BJ 



2S2 Phih.^ophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

belief impossible. So I experienced a shift of world-vieWj from a pLoiis 
one to a secular one. I lost any idea that philosophy could provide nie 
with a rational foundation for faith. 

Thcii I came into contact with Charles Hartshorne^ as different a 
philosopher from McKeon as one could get Understanding reality was 
his life. His classes were an introduction into his conversation with 
himself on these matters, one that was Roing on before the class started^ 
and continued after It ended. I was attracted to this immediately, and, 
over the years, this attraction grew. I became aware that one didn^t 
have to choose between different world-views. There was a third wayp 
one that took advances In modernity seriously - a process way of 
studying reality, In which 'taeconiing' Is more important than 'bclng^ 
and 'events^ are more important than 'substances'. God was now In 
everything, but not in a pietistic way. I didn't want to evaluate tL too 
quickly like McKcon and say This Is just another system/ On the other 
liand, I adantt that what I go on lo say is confessional I speak as a 
ft"ocess thinker. 

Hartshorne emphasized arguments^ but in a context where the data 
seemed to support them. I( depends on seeing the world in a certain 
w^ay. What attracted me was not the arguments so much as the world- 
view. Is that reasonable? I won't pursue the larger tale which would 
have to be told to answer that question. 

I then became aware of differences between Hartshorne and White- 
head. I wa& learning about the latter through the formcrj and my 
teachers were neo-naturallsts. These teachers said that changes In the 
twentieth century opened up the world In a new way. The process thus 
revealed Included human beings. They called this process 'God'. 1 was 
helped more by Hartshorne than by Wieman and wrote my master's 
thesis criticizing the latter in a way 1 w^ould modify today- So I was 
exposed to disputes within the Process family, 

I find Whitehead's speculative philosophy congenial. It is a philosophy 
which advances hypotheses. Vou study a particular Held as rigorously 
as you can (although you have your presuppositions). You appreciate 
some factors and then see that a full apprcclaLion of them takes you 
into another field of study. This is an endless task. It Is a cosmological 
task. For Whitehead, science gives us the most reliable basis for judge- 
ment concerning what we arc given, Tlie subjective side of things is 
explained more tuUy in religion. 

Religion is a global phenomenon. We cannot confine ourselves In our 
studies to traditional Christianity. If you look at physics^ the current 
theories are aheady loaded with presuppositions. Many of them owe 



Dz. niiiiip^ 2s;^ 

their form to substance-thinking. Paradoxes arise from that conccptu- 
alUy. So wc don^t settle for prcsonl hypollicscs^ but check to see whether 
you can arrive at better ones. This is true of religion, too, so the task is 
essentially tevisioiiist. 

For WTiitehead and Harthsorne, to be is to be constituted by all that 
ha5 happened in the past, and one must form oneself creatively out of 
that- I find an analog in Buddhism^ with its non-substantial vievs' of 
rchRLon. We are Johnny-come-latelj^'s in this respect. God is the 
supremely inclusive real. All that happens in the world happens in 
God. This is radical interactive thinking. It could be argued that so far 
from being revisionist^ this is a more faithful reflection of Biblical 
thought than classical tbcisrn. 



E: I want to make four points on matters not said in my paper- 
First, what is philosophy of religion? This involves asking, WTiat is 
philosophy? As I understand it, li is motivated by an existential question 
which asks whether existence has a meaning as part of an encompassing 
whole, how should wc conduct ourselves given that this is our lot? 
Philosophy attempts to clarify these questions. 

But although philosophy is motivated by these questions, it is not 
conslitLUed by them. It is constituted by theoretical questions about 
the meaning of our various practices. Reflection sees whether these are 
valid- Here I am indehted to Habermas's conception of philosophy as 
criUcally motivated self-understanding. This U love of wisdom or 
authentic self-understanding. 

Philosophy has two related taskis. First, it has a purely analytic task, 
that of elucidating tlie conditions for the possibility of self-understand- 
ing. Thi^i task results in a transcendental metaphysics, because IL is an 
attempt to elucidate the necessary conditions of human discourse 
as such- Second, it has the task of crilically evaluating the various 
answers which have been given to the existential question I mentioned 
at the outset. I want to formulate an answer to that question. Here^ 
philosophy and theology have a mutual contact. 

My second point arises out of my preoccupation as a Christian the- 
ologian. Theology or philosophical theolog;^^ is reflection on a religious 
tradition. So the data here are already religious. My particular concern 
is with the distinctive claims clauiied to be valid by Christian witness. 
Here wc have to do with the claim which is specific in Us content 
Involvlnj^ a reference to Jesus Christ. This witness is possible for any 
person by our common experience. So this claim necessarily involves 
philosophical reflection- Christian witness is historically determined 



2S4 Pfiihsnphy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%t Century 

and must be dealt with histoFicaLly, but it also involves asking what 
kind of meaning this witness involves. This task is iio( only theological^ 
but eminently philosophical Arc Christian claims as valid as they 
claim to be? These ciaims are validated in the same \^'ay as wc validate 
other claims. 

Third, given that I am a Process theologian, let mc say a few things 
about that. Process philosophy seems to nic to Ik the right philosophy- 
right, not because I am a Christian, but because it articulates better 
than any other philosophy^ the understanding of existenccj and the 
necessary conditions of that existence- Here 1 think of it as my 
primary source. It continues to prove itself in my task as a Christian 
theologian. 

Fourtlij let mc indicate where I find myself at odds with most of my 
fellow Process philosophers and theologians. Process thought has a 
transcendental metaphysics. Because ft is an answer to an existential 
question it implies both a metaphysics and an ethics. Metaphysics is an 
explanation of ultimate reality_ But, thcn^ it is essential not to confuse 
the metaphysical conditions with factual slaLcs of affairs. This is a lesson 
to be learned from VVittgenstein- 

Takc the example of myth. A myth is the condition of certain facts 
being the case, but it is not itself a further fact. We see the trouble that 
conies from treating; metaphysics as a fact in the worl; of T hales and 
other pre-Socratics- This is precisely the confusion we find in White- 
lieadf but it persists even mote in Hartshorne in his notion of a 
psychicalist ontology. My own w^ay has been to concentrate on those 
questions which arc of concern to everyone. We see this not only in 
Kant^ but also in Duns Scotus. 

V: Wouldn't you say that a general ontology and metaphysics is neces- 
sary for the Christian faith, but not the categorical metaphysics we are 
offered? 

E'. The consequence of the metaphysics wc are offered so often is that it 
does not recognize that God is not a fact, taut the condition of the pos= 
sibility of any fact- So ^God exists' is not a statement of fact 

A\ U says that T^ecoming' is more Important than 'taeing', and that 
'Gvents' are more important than substances_ Vou also say that every 
event is internally related to its past. 1 find that wildly implausible. The 
world may have started in a different way but 1 can't see that that 
affects who I am. You say that ihis reasoning has its ancestry in Hcgcl^ 
but that doesn't make it less criticizable. 



Wc have lo distinguish between things. Is a tabic an event? It is an 

instantiation of various properties. Bui this is not iruc of other things. 
Am I just a bundle of feelings? If my brain is transplanted In another 
pcrsonj have 1 survived the operation? 

Ui As long as you think in lenns of substances and attributes you can't 
see the problem. Take an cjcampte from physics. It was thought that 
tlic understanding of light as light waves required the postulation of 
ether - there must he a substance uitderlying the events. There is no 
ether, but people still talk of tight waves. Uul the notion of 'waves^ 
itself comes from substance-thinking. We must ask whether we can 
have events without postulating substances, and some are now 
retelling quantum theory from this point of vicw. 

Now think of a moment in human experience. Antecedent moments 
are ftjnclionin^ in that moment. When we hear a word, there is the 
relation of the present to antecedent experiences. That is an itilcrnal 
relation which enters into memory; perception and causality^ and 
which differs fiom postulating or thinking of an underlying T 

E: I am puzzled by Fs distinction l:^ctvrecn necessary conditions and 
factually. Are there necessary propositions that arc facts? As loi^g as a 
statement is not a fact it cannot have existential import. Can't we say 
that what is necessarily true exists, but is not a faci? 

Ml I criticize the metaphysics out of which your question ariS^. I want 
to re-emphasize the importance of internal rehlions as U did to A. For 
examplCn it throw-s hght on the doctrine of the Trinity. VVc can be 
brought to see that each person of the Trinity has no identity apart 
from the others. 

A: That notion is congenial to mCj and I have argued as much. The Son is 
the Son by virtue of the Father, and the Holy Spirit Is what It is by virtue 
of the Father and the Son. But this is not an example of a metaphysical 
truth wliich would hold in all cases. 



D: U says in his paper, 'It is true that coercive power can destroy and 
kill, but only persuasive power can give life and evoke love.' [ do not 
see this_ Surely coercive or persuasive power may destroy and kill. 

U: I agree the matter is more coi^iiplex tlian tire way I put it 'Persuasive 
power' is a shorthand way of referring to something I want to empha- 
size. Much ot" what we are at present has been determined by the past, 
but there is also the possibility of the novel in the occasion. This 



2S6 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 



depends on creative responses lo the possibilities which present them- 

■^olvps from thr nsst. 



selves from the past. 



C: 1 think that tay persuasive power you mean a ceriain kind of power^ 
not ihc one poi%Tr whicli may be used persuasively or cocrcivcly. I am 
reminded of Kierkegaard's remark liiaL love cannot conquer by force. 
That marks out the kind of power love has. 

f/r Agreed. 

C: But now, correct me if I am wrong, 1 have heard Process theologians 
speak in b way which disturbs me about God being limiEcd in what he 
can do, as though this were a limitation- liut if God's only power is the 
pow^ei of love, and love cannot eonquei by force (tliat is^ that sugges- 
tion does not make sense), then it is highly misleading to call that a 
ilmitatioTi, or to say, as some do, that God does the best he can, or that 
God has jjood days and bad days. 

U: 1 think the theologians you refer to arc anxious to rid us of a magical 

conception of power where God is concerned. 

C: I understand that, and accept the negative point. It has ahvays 
seemed to me a jarring aspect of the Passion story when Jesus sa>^ that 
If he wanted to he could call a legion of angels to get him off the cross. 
It seems like a religious version of those bad films which end with 
'Here comes the cavalry'. 

No, It is the positive account of Process theologians which worries n\e 
when they refer to limitations in God, and so forth. If love cannot con- 
quer by force, it follows that it can be rejected. At the heart of Chris- 
tlanlty is a radical rejection of love? a rejection so severe that it involves 
tlie one w^ho reveals the love being deprived of an informed deadi, such 
as that of Socrates. Instead he cries out, ^My God, my God, why hast 
thou abandoned me?"" To reveal how^ far love can go, Jesus becocnes the 
transparent vehicle for it, the price of w^hich is his sense of abandon- 
ment. I am unhappy at calling this a limitation since, rather, it Is the 
paradigm of the expression of what divine compassion is. So far from 
being a llinilationj it Is said to be a full and final revelation. 

I: In your autobiographical account [/, you told us of how you moved 
beyond your early pietism, how you came to embrace a secular per- 
spective, but, then, in time, moved beyond that. You gave up your old 
objectivism and practised theological praxis. Why, then, have you 
come to rest in Process thought? This seems to be a final resting place. 



D,Z. niiilip^ 2S7 



But, dialect ically, a genuine pluralism would ask to continue stTugglmK- 
Arc you still struggling? 

U: That^s fine. You speak as one who is open to wh^it Is new. So you're a 
process thinker whether you like it or not. Bui, seriously, Tm certainly 
seHI struggling. I want things to change- In these latter days 1 have 
devoted more attention to economic factors than to technical issues in 
philosophy and thcolog^^ There arc new movements I l:fcad to come to 
grips with- Feminism made me rethink many questions. But I suppose 
tlie biggest hurdle I had to face was Black Theology. 1 am a descendant of 
a slave-owning family who were leaders of the Confederacy 5o these 
matters w^erc painful for me. 1 was made to realize how many of our the= 
ological calcgocies reflect certain assumptions ahoul White supremacy- 
I could deal with Latin American economic issues far more easily than 

r 

1 could face up to Black Theology. So I am sLtll struggling. There arc 
movements represented in Lhis conference, such as Postmodernism, 
which I recognize as ha\1ng major implications for our times. If I were a 
younger man I would have attempted to address It thoroughly. So 1 am 
not complacent at alL 



19 

Voices in Discussion 

D.Z. Philtips 



In the last discussion session graduate studcnis adtiicsscd six questions 
to some of the participants. 

F 

V: I have a question l:or V. When you arc attracted to notions of empti- 
ness in Buddhism you seem tp see them as reflecting stales of reality 
which are truer than other states of a more substantive kind. But isn^l the 
reference to ^^cmptUies^' part of the giammar of a Buddhist pcrspccLlve 
which is one among many? 

U: You may well l>e rights and you ale ccr tainl)' entitled to advance that 
view- All I can say by way of reply is that in my expertence the teachings 
about 'emptiness' or the experience of it do not seem to be captured by; 
your su^j^estion. 

W: I spoke of a liberating totality in liberaticn theology. V™o-fe to 
decide what is liberating? What oitc regards as liberating progress^ 
another may icgard as decline. 

/: This reference owes much to the tradition of Hegel and Marx in 
which society is seen as a totahty. LJut that totality' may be oppressive 
and totalitarian. Now^ to the extent that there is a society at all there 
will be a certain amount of agreeinent in language, law, customs, and 
so on. But there will also be the cry of the oppressed^ since some laws 
may be oppressive. A philosopher reflcciing on these soczial realiiieSn on 
the importance of tradition and consensus, can also be a political 
activist who seeks to bring about changes In those iaws. 

X: I want to ask a related question of F. When Levlnas speaks of under- 
standing and responding to the othcr^ the face of the other is the face of 
the widow and the orphan. This pves the response a concrete context. 



2SS 



DZ. niiilip^ 2S9 



But with Derrida, the matter seems open-ended, and so chaolic. ITie 
face of llic other is any face. But what if it is the face of a killer? 

F: Dcrrida does derive his views from Levin as. But he savs that there is 
no set of rules which determines these matters. There is no hospitality 
williout risk- It is not a formal notion. The homicidal rapist is not the 
other. The otiier is tlie one who requires help. 

5: As K pointed out in his paper, there are many concepts of truth in 
rclij^toii. [ want to ask O and H, tlierelorej wliy this point cannot be an 
answer to the difficullics of HalKrmas's criteria of vindication with 
respect to religious belief, 

O: I tliink the reason wliy I don^t want to embrace that response is that 
it privatizes truth. Public vindication seems to be surrendered. 

$: But, surely, yoti don't think that makes it a free-for-alL There are crite- 
ria whicli arc internal to perspectives. People may take an absolute stand 
oai ihese^ since^ as i said before 'absolute^ need not mean ^universat'. 

O: I agree, but the evidence would stLll be extremely difficutt to assess. 

H: 1 think the question shows the need for a critique of Habermas. How 
do we look for a vindication of religious expcitence? it is not going to be 
a matter of sLcaightfoiward inference. This is because it brings something 
which cannot l>e found in the worlds but belongs to a notion of the lim- 
its of the world- Habermas's public criteria need to be supplemented by 
inner criteria which recognize the affective character of religious belief. 
These criteria will involve spiritual and ethical values. Habernias can 
never arrive at tliese as long as he bases future progress on whatever 
the interests of people happen to be. 

Y: I want to askA and K about their different notions of the relations 
between belief and practice. 

A: I want to distinguish between belief and practice, because what 1 do 
about the beliefs I have is always a further question- Some beliefs are 
more relevant to my purposes than others. I may learn as part of my 
education that William the Conqueror invaded Britain in 1066^ but 
that belief may have Jittle to do with my immediate purposes. 1/ I 
believe in God I must still decide what I am goiiig to do al^out my 
belief. The most natural and rational response is worship, but that is 
only one response among a number to thai belief- 

K: I think there arc important diffe^h^s tKtiveen t>elicfs- There are 
thousands of empirical beliefs that 1 have which 1 am indifferent to. 



290 Pfiih.wp!iy ofRi'lii^mr m ttn! 21%i Century 

They have lltHc^ if any^ effect on mc. With others, like belief in ^avitYf 
1 am certain and have no choice. With moral and religious beliefs it is 
different a^ain. HerCn there are internal relations between belief and 
practice. So I disagree with A. You can^t dislinguish beti^vcen a belief in 
generosity and what you do about it. If I am never generous, then I 
can't be said to believe in generosity, since to Ix^licvc in generosity is to 
be generous- Belief in God is like this toOn since its primary form is 
'trust in God'. This is ivhat believing in God comes to. 

Z: Throughout the conference we have had different views expressed 
about the relation of philosophy to religion. T want to ask A, U, G and / 
to say what they think philosophy can do in tliis context. 

A: Philosophy can help religion in a number of eonlexts. Firstp it can 
clarify the crcdai elements in religion. Second^ it can assess arguments 
for or against the tnith of religion. Gregory of J^yssa is a model in this 
respect. Thirds a lot will depend on the way philosophy is practised- If 
it Is done with analytic rigour, philosophy can help by giving a clear 
presentation of the ideas involved in religion. So altliough religion does 
not need philosophy's help In all contexts, it certainly does in some. 

U: The strong separation of philosophy from religion is a problem of 
modernity. If we look to India or China we see that piiilosophy is a 
way of life. I prefer the ancient view to the modern akernative. I 
believe philosophy can help us to say 'Christ is Lord of air, and that 
dierefore there are gocxl philosophical reasons for saying diis. 

G: Philosophy can certainly lielp rcltgjon in meeting ad ftoc objections 
to it. But philosophers aren't omnicompetent in this respect. If, for 
example^ someone tries to iink a religious movement w^ith economic 
decline^ then what I need is not a philosopher, but an economist. 
Simtlarly, philosophers can't tackle the problems of delinquency. 

More positively, the model i am attracted to is that of Clement of 
Alexandria, who saw the life of the mind, in our case philosophy, as 
itself a mode of worship and thanks^javing. So to do one's best to 
display what Christ's Lordship means for art. justice, and so forth, is, for 
me, at the heart of my calling as a phalosophet. On the other hand, it is 
important to recognize that philosophy can't save you, 

J: I just want to re-emphasize two things I have said before. First, in 
what philosophical attenticn asks of us in relation to the world, there 
is a spiritual dimension. Second, in giving this attention there is often 
a need to save religion from what philosophy has done to it. Hcre^ we 
need philosophy to overcome philosophy- 



Index 




1 


Abraham, 15S, 163, 179 


anthropology, 


1 


■ L ^ - 

acqu^iintance 


psychology 197 


1 


belief, 54-5 


teliyioHr 50^ 56 


1 


deductive argumentSr 54 


anthropomorphism, IZ. Z55-6 


1 


entities, 53 


apologetic arjfumients, 24-6, Mi 


1 


facts, S.^-4 


apophaticSj ISB^ 174, 253 


1 


Addiiis^ MaiiSyn^ 22-i!i 


Aquinas, Thomas (St}, 


1 


Adams, l^bextf 24 


deductive aryuirients, 6, 31 


1 


Adorno, Theodor W,^ 


existence of God, 104, 109-10, 2^ 


1 


art, 221. 248 


faith, 25, 32 ' 


1 


Califcrnian exile, 19B 


first principles, '^6 


1 


determinQle negation. 199. 219 


methodoiog}^, 246 


1 


En Lighten mem, 199, 244 


philosophical tlieism^ 4, 22 


1 


Frankfurt .Scl-Loof, 19:^ 


Aristotle, 


1 


Habeima-s, 2()h5-7, 221-2 


creativity, 27 


1 


Hegel, 199-200 


First Mover, 3 


1 


identity, 205 


inference, 77 


1 


inatejia3i_sm. 205-6 


metaphysics, 1S6 


1 


metaphysics, Zt>S 


moral reasoning, 33 


1 


JiegatEve dialectics, 205 


art, 200,221,233-4, 24H 


1 


positivism. 2(K>-1 


athieism, 


1 


leflection and knowledge, 200 


atrocities, 205 


1 


ae^hetics, z:^t)^ ZJSJi-5 


InEeSlectua] passivity, 214 


1 


al-GhazalE, Abu Hamid Mohamraed^ 


Marxism, 198 


1 


26 


metaphy.^Ecs^ 254 


1 


AJslon, William P., 2^i. 40, 51-2, 65 


methodoJogica] atheism, 2J?0, 235j 


1 


American Academy of RelEgion. 263 


246-7 


1 


analytical pJnLcxsophy, 


pha3oso[^J:iicat theism, 5, 36 


1 


Continental ph][osophy, 17 


sophistication, 4, 26 


1 


Tion-theastic religion, 33 


theism compared, 2<>4 


1 


ontological arguments, 5, '^5 


Wittgensteinianism, 4S, SS 


1 


RefoFQied Epi5temology, 15 


Atonement^ 23-4 


1 


theistic re ij:ion. ?.?j, 65 


Audi, Robert, 7S 


1 


Wiltgenstein^ 16 


Augustine of Hippo (St), 


1 


Anselm CSt)j 


behef, 56 


1 


belief, 109 


CiV^fcssionSj 159 


1 


contempEation, 26 


con temp ation^ 26 


1 


existence of God, 34^ 104 


Derrida, 159-60 


1 


faith, 35 


faith, 42, 49, SS 


1 


inquiry, 26-7 


love of God, 1 74 


1 


ontclogical arguments, _1I4-Sj 110 


Austin, Jolm Langsham, 164 


1 


religious fraiiLework^ -^^ 


Averroes, Ibn Kushd, 26 


1 


antecedent judgements, xii^ xv^ 32 


A\'icenna (ibn 5ina), 26 
291 


J 



292 Index 




1 


awareness, acquaintance Vkith entEtieSj 


lequirements, 12 


1 


53 


testimony, 77-S 
tnith-reievant merits, 42-3 


1 


Barth, Karl, IZ 


warrant see warrant theory' 


1 


basic beiief^ 


Way of Ideas theorists^ 50 


1 


ambiguous usaj^e, 46-7 


Wittgenstein, 44, 46-7, 10<>-2, 


1 


ccmpetmijbeliefs. 90 


127-8, 38-9 


1 


immediate heJief, 4Sj 47, 9L 


belief formation, 


1 


lEiediationr 91 


excellences, 69 


1 


properly basic, 15, 45, 79-BO, K6-B 


inference, 5 1 


1 


wanant theory, 45^ 77 


mediate/immediate processes, 32, 


1 


bnsica ists. 


91 


1 


see aiso Reformed Epistemology 


modes, 37 


1 


evidence, 66 


Eentham^ Jeremy, 121 


1 


non-inferentaal justlhers, 57 


Eerkeiey, George, 33, 121 


1 


Baudrillard, Jean. 155 


Bernstein, Richard. 1S2 


1 


Bavinck, Herman, 42 


Bible, 


1 


Bayes'5 Theorem^ 7, 10, i::^, 21, 32 


apocalypse, 257 


1 


Beardslee, William A., 263 


Bible God, 236, 259 


1 


belief. 


Epistles see EpisEies 


1 


acquaintance, 34-5 


graven images. 2<X1 


1 


basic 5ff basic belief 


NT see New Testament 


1 


comnriunitv, 136 


OT see 03d Te5tame]it 


1 


ccntinuity, 136 


philosophical sense, 186 


1 


depth of ingressicn, 46-7 


pnDcess thought, 253 


1 


empiricssm, 97, 102, 122 


BlanchoE, 157, 161 


1 


evaluation, niodes, S7 


Bloom, Allan, 1 56 


1 


evidentialisE challenge, 4K-30 


Bonhoeffer, Dietrich, 163, 255 


1 


folly/foolishness, 1Z7-S 


boundary, Zi:)4 


1 


hard-wired, 50, 90 


Bouwsma, O.K., 4S-9, 86, R9 


1 


historic facE^, 1 35 


Boyle ectuve5„ 24 


1 


ideally formed, 53—4 


Brahman, 256 


1 


immediate see immediate belief 


Bruce, RD., 91 


1 


inductive, 53 


Buddhism. 256. 260, 273, 2S3, 2S8 


1 


Inference, 31, 34, 51, 77 




1 


jnstlflcation^ 73 


Calvin^ John,, 


1 


mediate, 46, 51-2 


faith, 25, 32 


1 


Hieiits set' doxastic m;erit5 


religious anthropology, 50, 56 


1 


metaphysics, 34, 1<K>, 146-7 


religious, knowing, 65 


1 


normal/ordinary/ieascnable, 127-S, 


Calvin College, 4^ 49,86 


1 


L3C 

' ■ r F , 


Calvin ians, 

-■- - • • . 


1 


probability^ xia, xv, 7-11, 13-14, 23, 


foundationaEism, 79-80, S7 


1 


32, 97, 122 


neo-Calvanism, 41-2, 4^-9, 64, K3 


1 


pmpositional content, 54-6 


Caputo^John D.. XEii, 153-66^, 167^ 


1 


rational grounding. 43, 4S, 56 


174, 176 


1 


rationality^, xii, 15j 34-5 


Cartesian arguments, J^O-1, 157-3^ 


1 


reasons, 43-4 


199 


1 


Reformed Epistemology, 15, 27, 44 


Cathoiics, 66, 2S1 


1 


leligious experience^ 31 


causality, 25S, 261 


J 





Index 293 


1 


Cavell, Stanley, ! 16-17, 145, 147^ 


Wittgenstein ianism, 16, 103, U>6 


1 


ceitatnty. 


Churchill, Winston S,, 89 


1 


fakh, 32, 137 


Clarke, Samuel, 21-2, 24 


1 


fundamenEa isnir 167 


classical foundationali^m, 41 j 4S, 


1 


unceitam beljef^ 12 


4^-50, 52, SB 


1 


choBCEr order in the world, 32 


Clement of .Alexandria, 42, BS, 290 


1 


Chopp, Rebecca. 155 


CEimacus, 102 


1 


Cluislianr William A_, 178 


Cobb, John B.^ xiv, xvi, 251-65, 


1 


Christian phalosopherSr rt-Jij^ious 


266-73, 275, 277-6 


1 


philosophy, ku 


coheFentist th^eory, 46, 52 


1 


Christian EheologianSr 


ColeridjDre, 24 


1 


Atonement, 23 


community, 


1 


cosmoSog)^, vi 


belief, 136 


1 


desi^j^r 3 


Derfidj. 162, li^l, 187 


1 


eschatcjoyVr l^i-'* 


hospitality, 162 


1 


God's image, 12 


pub ic interest, IBl 


1 


Lncanidtlonj 2?p 


con^sion, 145^ 147 


1 


process thought, 252. 261. 266, 2B4 


contempbtion, 


1 


Trinitv. 2:^ " 


inquiry, 26 


1 


ChiistianiEyr 


Plato, 90 


1 


Byddhism compjred, 260 


prayer, 26 


1 


Calvinism sei^ Cdlvmians 


Wittgenstein, 9CJ 


1 


C-aEholks, 66, ZSl 


Wittgensteinianism, Kii, xiv 


1 


"CoheFeni worfdvleiv^ 265 


Cooke, Maeve, xlli, 211-43 


1 


conversions, 4, 137 


Copernicus, Nicolas^ 81 


1 


credibilitv,. 17S 
J - 


cosmo og>^ 


1 


esi:hato]og5."r 133, 176-7 


Christian theologians, 3 


1 


exEernal criticism;, 106 


existence of God, 110, 131 


1 


Horkheimei, 214 


Kalam, 26 


1 


intellectuals, 42 


process thought, 251-2, 261-3, 2^8 


1 


Jesus Jt-f Jesus Chiist 


Cieduiity' Principle^ 72 


1 


Judgement Day. 02-3, 146, 193 


Critical Theory, 


1 


love, 2S6 


Adorno see Adoino. Theodor W. 


1 


martyrdom, 23 


discussion, 244-H 


1 


Method] sEs, 281 


economic necessity, 196 


1 


Nietzsche, 106. 15t, 1B6 


Frankfujt School, 193 


1 


perfectionism, 147 


tiabcrmas .^t^e Habermas, Jiirgen 


1 


Puritans, i^Z 


historical wrongs, 206 


1 


reasonableness^ 122 


Hovkheimer ^ee Hoikheimer, Max 


1 


redemption, 128 


justice, 211 


1 


fefofmed-Presbyterian tradition. 41 


knowledge, 21 1 


1 


levelation of God, 2.SS, 25S 


metaphysics, xiii, xv 


1 


salvation, 1 ZH, 1 i^S, 245 


open project, 1 93 


1 


sJn, 116 


practical intent, 21 1-43 


1 


suffering, 255 


reason, 163 


1 


theism, 6S 


reJiglon, 193-243 


1 


Trinity-, 23, 2£55 


riva] programmes, 1 7 


1 


witness, 23:i 


truth, 211 


1 


Wiltgenstein, 1^2-4, 137 


cults, predictions, 132-3 
293 


J 



294 Imii^x 




1 


cultural studies, 155 


■^my leligion", 159 


1 


Cupitt. Don, 17 


negative Eheo3og>^ 160, 167-9 


1 


c),"nkism^ 204 


ontotheolog}-', 16K-9 
openness to everything, xiii 


1 


Day, Doiothy, 16JE 


Other without history and society. 


1 


d€ EoQT, Jesse^ 87 


167-85 


1 


deconstmction^ 


postmodernism, 48, 158^^^ 


1 


affirmaEion of imposBible^ 160-1 


leligion as messianic hope^ 


1 


ccncrete messiiinismi, 163 


169-8?!^ 


H 


detenninate it'Li>;ii;'nr 177 


^I^on without religion, 15fi-9. 


1 


fajth, 175 


174, 76, 187, 189-90 


1 


feminism. 2fi3 


SE Augustine, 159-60 


1 


God, 169 


spntencesj 17 


1 


hi^toric^i ur^encieSr 1713—4 


singulaiity, 170-1, 177, 179, 1S2, 


1 


messsanic poitmodernism, 159, 161 


187 


1 


modernist critiques, 158 


Descartes^ Rene, 


1 


negativ^e theo3ogyr 16S^9 


autonomous subject, 189 


1 


poiitics^ 178 


Cartesian arguments, 80-1, 157-S, 


1 


proiiess thoughi, 26^^ 


199 


1 


scepticism, 14S, 182 


criEicai of given, 17J5 


1 


totalities, 167, 1S2 


design argument 3,, 110 


1 


wholly other, 161 


determinacy, 169, 171, 174, 176-7, 


1 


iieduclive aiguments, 6, M^ 54 


183 


1 


De3euze,GiJies, 155, 157 


deEerminate negation. 199,206-7, 


1 


democracy, 156, 172-3, 177, 179, 1S6 


212, 21S-9 


1 


DemociiEus, 99-130 


determinism. 257 


1 


Denida, Jacques, 


Dewey, John, 219 


1 


CirctimffssiGfs^ 155 


diaEectics, 


1 


community, 162^ li^l, JS7 


dialectical materialism, ZlZ-15 


1 


concrete messianisms. 163 


Enlightenment, 19S-9 


1 


democracy 172-:^, 177, 179 


negative dialectics^ 205 


1 


detemiinacy, 169, 171, 174, 176-7 


difference. 


1 


diffefence, 16G^9, 171, J?:^, 175, 


Derrlda, 168-9, 171, 173, 175, ISS. 


1 


IK.^, 1R6-S 


1K6-S 


1 


discussion, li46-90 


postmodernism, is:-i-4j 156-7 


1 


dogmflj ISS 


WIttgensteinj xv, 1KB 


1 


ethical concerniir xv 


disrourse. 


1 


^ait]-i, 179 


5ff tiho Janguflge 


1 


hospitality. 159. 162, 164, 189 


illogicahty. U>7-8 


1 


hyperousiokjgy, 16tJ, 16S 


kenosis, 16S 


1 


impossible/possaHe, 161, 169 


meaningfulness. 21 


1 


in-coming, 161-2 


morality, 2S6 


1 


jQiJai:>m, 159-60, 16^ 


necessary conditions, xiv 


1 


justice. 162, 171-2, 177, 1K2, ISS 


negative theo]ogy, 168 


1 


Levinas, 15H, ISO, 1B6-7, 289 


postmodernism, 164-3 


1 


liberatioTi Eheology, 187 


process thought, xiv 


1 


Jibing with other^ 187 


super-facft, xvi 


1 


metaphysics, 1K6, 1S8 


theology, 235 


1 


moral aporia, 181 


Wittgensteinianism, kVi 


J 





Itui^x 295 


1 


divine, 


en lilies^ 


1 


^ff also God 


acquaintance^ 53 


1 


-covenant. 13-3 


existent things, 99-lCK> 


1 


mutabiht}'';, 254 


epistemologyi 


1 


necessity^ ^^^^ 


sff atso foundationalism 


1 


omnipotenize, 258-9, 267, 269-70 


empiricism, 121-2 


1 


omniiCBence, 256-7^ Z59, 267 


epistemic hookup. 7^^., 75 


1 


simpJicity^ 42 


epLstemic practices^ 57 


1 


dogma. 


Kant, 20:i 


1 


Deirldla, 158 


knowJedje, 121 


1 


dogmatizatlon, 167 


meta-epistemology, 41, ^). 


1 


HoTkheimer, 198 


psyche ogT.', 12^!> 


1 


RefoFTTied Eplatemology, 44 


reformed sue Reformed 


1 


doxdslic evaluation, 58 


Epistemologji- 


1 


DoxastEC Ideal^ 54-6 


scepticism, 201-2, 205 


1 


doxastic meriti. 


EplstJes^ 


1 


evidence, 72 


Corinthians, 12, 127-B, 13S, 150 


1 


foundationaiiani. 51-Z 


Ephesians, 82 


1 


immediate belled, 44, 46-7^ 52 


Romans, 3, 12, a2, 140 


1 


natural theoloj^^^ 44 


St Augustine, 56 


1 


non-foundataonahst, 46^ 51 


eschatoSogjr, 133-4, 169. 172, 176-7, 


1 


p3uraljty/mu[t][j]6city, 4.^., 6S 


182 


1 


raEionaEit}-;, 6^ 


essentiahsm, 133 


1 


doxasiic pracEiC'CS^ Bti 


ethics, 171,233, 2544 


1 


doxastlc sickness^ 69 


Evans, C, Stephen, 27, 32 


1 


doxastic sin, 69 


evidence, 


1 


Draper, P^ul. 23 


antecedent udgements^ Kii, 32 


1 


Duns Scotus. John, 4, 284 


basjca lists, 66 

communitarian relation, 72, S6 


1 


Eckhart, Johannes (Measterj^ ISOf 


criteria. IS 


1 


275 


cumulative effect, 31 


1 


Edwards, Jonathan, 21-2, 2S, 27, i^Z 


doxastic merits^ 72 


1 


EitiotEon, i^llh, J^C* 


e>Li5tence of God, 7-8, 13, 31 


1 


^nipincisniij 


inference^ 66-7, 69, 76-K 


1 


behet 97, 102, 122 


Jesus Christ, 11, 66 


1 


British phi oRophy, 121 


language, 133—4 


1 


empirical laws, 24 


neutral evidence, xii 


1 


epistemiology, 121-2 


predictions, 132 


1 


■eKisteniie of God^ 109 


reasons, 97-8 


1 


process thought, Z51. 26B-9 


theisEic beliefs, 66 


1 


emptiness, 256, 28S 


warrant theory, S6 


1 


Engeis, Friedrich, 19S 


evtdentialism, 


1 


Enlightenitientj 


challenge, 48-50 


1 


dialectic, 198-9 


deficiencies, 65 


1 


morality. 230 


foundationahsm. 76. 79, 87 


1 


nan'ow concept, 2f)L 


nanow conception, xii 


1 


negation of optimism^ 244 


persuasive argument, 32 


1 


pessimism, I9S 


polemical partners, 66, 76 


1 


lationaEity, xii, 4i, 153, 177 


rationality-evidentiahsmj 69-71, 76 


J 



296 Jmii^x 




1 


e^identialism - contimitd 


justification, 103! 


1 


lesiTonse to Wolteri^trifff, 64-82 


ontotheology, 16H-9 


1 


sensib e evidenti^ i^m, 72^3, 75-6, 


process thought, 252 


1 


Bl-Z 


seeing jtv 


1 


warrani theory^ 73-6 


theoretical activitj", 51 


1 


ei-il^ 


virtue^ 11, 25 


1 


evidential prob em, 2j 


faUit/^ 14fi.279 


1 


God's tzlnizum^ 2i 


feminism, 262-3, 2S7 


1 


greater goods, 13 


feuerbachj Ludwig, 197, 24J 


1 


moral re&ponseivr 144 


fideism, 16, 103, lOB, 125, 130-1 


1 


existence of God^ 


Flew^ Andrew, 2 


1 


Christian theologians^ ■^^ 


Flint, Thomas. ZI-2 


1 


confirmation theory, 7 


Foucault, Michel^ J5S 


1 


cosmoloj^^, IU\ 131 


foundationalism^ 


1 


cred^E Llatiiss^ 5 


bipartite structure definitive, 52 


1 


deductive arguments, 6, li] 


Calvinians, 79-80, 87 


1 


empirical hypofhesiSj 109 


classical, 41, 45. 49^0, 52, SB 


1 


evidence, 7, 8, i:^, 31 


doxastic merits. 51-2 


1 


HorkheinseT, 205 


evidentiaEism, 76, 79^ 87 


1 


inductive arguments, 6, ':^\ 


evidentialist ciiallenge, 50 


1 


inference, il, 34 


mediate/immediate distinction, 46, 


1 


logical necessity, S. ]54 


52,91 


1 


natural tlieolog>^, S, 6, 7-L4 


Tion-founda£iona9ism, 46, 51 


1 


objections, 1 1-4 


opposition, 45-6, 49 


1 


onEological arguments see 


Reformed Episteitiolog}", 76, 87 


1 


onlclogical arguments 


franc Es de Sales, 17 


1 


Protestants, 4 


Francis of Assise ^5t:i, 148 


1 


sophisEicated arguments, 12 


Freddoso, Alfred, 21-2 


1 


Wittgenstein, 9S-3^ 100-L 


Frege, Friedrich, 120 


1 


existential questions. 


Freud, Siginund, 65, 106, 144 


1 


plnEosapliv. xiv, 268-9 


fundamentalism, certainty, 167 


1 


process thought^ xiv^ xvi, 26S-9^ 




1 


27S 


Gealy, Waiford, xiii, 119-43 


1 


externalism, 73-6, SO-1 


Genera Relativity iGTR^ 8 
Gier, Nicholas, 264 


1 


iacls, 


God, 


1 


acquaintance, 53-4 


see also theism 


1 


historical, 97, 13^-5 


almighty, 259 


1 


super-facts, xvi 


anthropomorphism, 12,255-6 


1 


faculties, 


Bible God, 256, 259 " 


1 


belief-foiming, 49^ 52 


CTeativit>; 256, 271, 275 


1 


epistemic, 27, 34 


deconstmction, 169 


1 


unbeheverSj 33 


education, 13iii 


1 


faith, 


existence see existence of God 


1 


apo ogetic arguments, 24-S 


^God-talk', 57, 60-62 


1 


certainty, '^2, 137 


goodness, 25 


1 


commitment^ 11-12, 25^ 100, 102 


HahK^rmas's vieu^, 221-4, 227-9 


1 


deconstmction, 175 


Horkhelmer's views, 197, 204-5 » 


1 


emotion, 13t 


211-14, 21 6-lS, 221^ 


J 





Itui^x 297 


1 


God - catitinued 


methodological atheism^ 2j{0j 2^5, 


1 


mcompr^^hensibalily, 174-3 


246-7 


1 


infinite powers IJ 


morality, 2?pO 


1 


'in^'isibJe things', jl 


natUFa asm, 228 


1 


love, 25 


normative theory, 22ti-9 


1 


muEabinty, 254 


post metaphysics, 22]?^, 226-9, 246 


1 


name of GhikI, Z14, Z20 


pragmatism, 2.il-Z 


1 


natiiidl Jaws, 23-4^ Jil-i3 


regulative ideal, xlil 


1 


negative theology^ 167-8 


religious meanings, oil 


1 


omnipotence, Z5K-9, Z67, 269-70 


self-understa]"iiJi]ig, 2S:-i 


1 


onnniscience, 256-7, Z59, 267 


semantic contents of rctigion^ 


1 


oi^Ti anfiag^^. 12 


229-:^ 1 


1 


person^ 274-S 


social hfe^ 21 1 


1 


persaai^ion, 25S, 2ES5-6 


truth, xiii, Z07-H. 221, 224-7, 


1 


physica objtictr 109, 13E: 


231-7, 243, 289 


1 


process thought, 254-9, 269-73 


unconditiona]]Ey, ZZ5-6. 229 


1 


properties, fi^9 


unconditioned, 208 


1 


realit)v ^iVj xvi, R9 


validity claims. 232-6 


1 


leferring to Gcd, 53-61, aa-9 


wisdom,, ZK3 


1 


simplicity, 42 


Haeckei, TheodoT. 197 


1 


spatial object, 38-9, 61 


Hart. Henk 40 


1 


things of God predicated^ 38^ 61-2 


Hartmann, Nicolai. 194 


1 


trust. probabiLily, xv 


Hartshorne, t^harles, 


1 


tzlmzum, Z'.i 


discourse, xlv 


1 


Whitehead's views, 255^, 270-1 


dLvine mutability, 254 


1 


whoUy other, 169-70, 186 


divine omnipotence. 270 


1 


wisdom^ 12K 


falsttication, 279 


1 


Goethe, Johann, 219 


God, Z5 4-5, 271-2 


1 


Go dman, 80 


metaphysics, Z55, Z72-3, 276 


1 


goodness, 


ohjettave modality, 276 


1 


-:^God, 25 


ontological arguments, 22 


1 


Plato, 3 156 


philosophical theism, 264 


1 


self'interest, 11, 25 


process thought, 251, 255 


1 


Gregory of Nyssa, 17, 35, 290 


psychicalism, Z72, ZH4 


1 


Griffin, David Ray, 26:^-1 


understanding reaiity, 2S2 


1 


+ 


Hegel, Georg, 


1 


Hahermas, Jiirgen, 


Adorno, 199-ZOO 


1 


Adorno, 206-7, 221-2 


being, Z03 


1 


aesthetics, 230. 231^-5 


critical of given, 173 


1 


communicative rationa it\'. 164 


determinate negation. ZJ2 


1 


ethical concerns, xv 


dialectics, 212^13 


1 


ethics, 231i 


failure of metaphysics, 20S 


1 


evolutionary processes, 22i^-9 


historical maieriaJtsm, 195 


1 


God, 221-4,227-9 


HorkhetmeT. 195, 19B-200, 21Z, 


1 


Hegel, 248 


24B 


1 


Horkheimei, 206-7, 221-7 


"J^arx, 195, 197, 201 


1 


Kant, 248 


reason, 196 


1 


language. Z06-7 


totaiitv. Zas 


1 


metaphysics, 229 


HeideEEer^ Martin, Aii, 173, 1B6, 1S9 


J 



298 Jmii^x 




1 


Hickjohn, 21 


truth, 196, 203^, 218^20, 221, 


1 


Hindui:>m, 26, 2S6 


225^, 231 


1 


historica] beliefs, 97, 102 


unconditioned, xiil, 20S, 244 


1 


hi5torlcai catastrophes, 173^ 198, 206 


utopianlsm, 221-2, 245 


1 


historical facts/piopositions, 97, 


hospitality, 159, 162, 154. 189 


1 


134-5 


Hume, David, 


1 


historica] materialism, 195-S, 201, 


causalitv', 2SS 


1 


205^ 


Doxastic Ideal, 55 


1 


Hobbe5f "IhoiiiaSr 121 


empiricism, 24, lZl-2 


1 


Hol3and,Joe, 263 


metaphysics. 253 


1 


Ho ocaust, 17:^, 198 


nacural theology, 4, 21 


1 


Holi^^rda, David^ 40 


phi osophica! theism, 12 


1 


Horkheimer, Max, 


^epticism, 122 


1 


Cdlifnrnian exik, 19B 


Husseri, Edmund. 1H9, 201 


1 


ChrisEiantty^. 214 


Huxley, Aldous, 148 


1 


ccrroboratlon iBew^ihmji^i, 21S-19 


Hyman, John, 99-101, 104, 108^9. 


1 


critique of reltgion, 19.^, 197-8,212 


119 


1 


determmate negation. 199, 206-7^ 


hyperousioiogy, 160, 16S 


1 


212,218-19 


hypocrisy, 146 


1 


dialectical iiiaterialism. 21Z-15 




1 


dogma. 19B 


Idealism, 213,245 


1 


early work, 194. 197, 212 


identity. 


1 


economic necessity^ 196 


language games, 123 


1 


Enlighienmeni, 198, 201, 244 


ronidentlty 205 


1 


epis.temolog>^ 201-2, 205 


postmodernism, 173 


1 


Frankfurt School, 19^ 


, totality, 1S7 


1 


God, 197, 204-5, 2I1-1-J, 21ti-ia, 


immediate belief, 


1 


221-i 


authenticity 88 


1 


Habermas, 2tl6-7, 221-7 


basic belief, 45, 47, 91 


1 


Hegel, 195, 19S^20(), 2I2^L:i, 248 


doxastic merits, 44. 46-7, 52 

1 ■ k* 


1 


historical materialism, 195-S, 201, 


mediate belief distinguished^ 46, 


1 


205 


51-2, 91 


1 


Edeahsm^ 21 :j, 245 


perception, 50 


1 


justice. 213 


ratio na tit)', 44 


1 


Kant, 201,230, 244 


impossible, 160-1, 168-9 


1 


melaphvsics^ 196, ■?02. 253 


inductive arguments, 6, 31, 54 


1 


oppression. 244-5 


inductive beliefs, 55 


1 


pessimism, 19B, 201-4, 213, 244 


inference, 


1 


positivism, 194, 20(-l 


belief, 31,34, 51, 77 


1 


postmodernismj 199 


epistcmic adequacy, 79 


1 


reason, 196, 207 


evidence, 66-7, 69, 76-S 


1 


reflection and knowlet^e^ 200 


existence of Cod, 3\, 34 


1 


religion's moral message, 215-16 


1nferen[ial propositions, 67 


1 


scepticism, 201-5. 244 


natural inferences, 82 


1 


semantic contents of religion, 


proper y inferential. 79-80 


1 


229-30 


rationality, 56 


1 


social contribution of religion, 


Reformed Epistemology, 76-9, 86 


1 


'212-15 


spnsaticns, 90 


1 


social life, 211 


simpEEciEy-dlsposation, 81 


J 





Itui^x 299 


1 


infinite allenty, 170-L 


non'inferential justafiers, 67 


1 


Tngraffia, Brian, 156^ 159 


rationality, 75 


1 


inquiry, contemplaticm^ 26 




1 


InsEitutc tor Social Research, 194 


Kanl, Immanuel, 


1 


intellection, intuitional content^ S'^ 


Aasdmitun^f 53 


1 


intelligibiityj 


autonomous subject, 1B9 


1 


negative theolog)^, 168 


causaHty. 25S 


1 


pra/er, UXS 


critique oi given, 173 


1 


Wiltgenslein, lZZ-3. 130 


eplsteiitolog^'. 203 


1 


Snternalism^ 7:^4, 79 


God. 60. 86 


1 


introsi>ection. mtuitlDnal content^ 53 


Habermas, 24S 


1 


intuition, S3 


HorkheiTTier, 201, 230, 244 


1 


Inwagen^ Peter Van, 23 


knowledge, 115 


1 


Irenaeui CSt^ 17 


inelapiiysics, 85, 203 
myths, 284 


1 


James, William, 27, 1S2, 219 


natura theology,'', 4, 21 


1 


Jesus Crhri&t, 


neo- Kantianism, 164^ 194 


1 


see aSso Christianitv 


phiBosophy of history^ 196 


1 


Ascension^ 149 


ratlonatEy grounded ic-lLgLon, 43^ 


1 


divine necessity^ 1^6 


SS. 172 


1 


evidence, 11^ 66 


regu arive ideal, 170 


1 


historical propositions. 97. I3S-7 


truth/morality/laste, 230 


1 


Lordship, 290 


Kelsen, Hans, 194 


1 


rassicn, Z.^, 2^6 


Kierkegaard, Sdren Aabye^ 


1 


Resurrection. 135^ 137-9, 146, 


ceitaintv of faith. 32 

_■ 


1 


14B-9, 198 


Climacus. 102 


1 


reveSation o*' God, 255, 25K 


Derrida, 15S, L^O 


1 


suffering, Zil, 255 


ethical/religfiouSj 170-1 


1 


mlness, l,^3e 283 


e>Listence of Gchl, 99 


1 


Judaism, 


God, JS6 


1 


Demda, 159^0, 163 


love, 7R6 


1 


eschatoiog^^, 176 


messianic postmodernism, 153, 156 


1 


historical clainb^, 135 


passion vi faith, 139 


1 


idolatry, 146 


postmodernism, 1K6 


1 


myt IS, Zm 


probahiEities and guarantees, 11 


1 


name of God, 220 


reason, 164 


1 


negative aspects^ 244 


uncertain belief^ 12 


1 


phllcscphers of refciglon, 22 


wholly othifr, 157 


1 


justice, 


King, Maitin Luther^ 163 


1 


Critical Theory, 211 


knowledge. 


1 


Derrida, 162, 171-2, 177, 132, 


Critical Theory, 21 1 


1 


1^8 


epistemoloffv, 121 


1 


HoTkheinier^213 


eKiernatiim, 74 


1 


Ra%v3s, 145 


internalism, 74 


1 


justification, 


Kant, 115 


1 


belief, 73 


religious knoiving, 65 


1 


connotations^ 74 


Wittgenstein, 115-6, 120-1 


1 


faith, 103 


Kretzmann, Noiman, 21 


1 


morality, 230 


Kuyper, Abraham^ 41, 65 


J 



300 Imii^x 






1 


language^ 


Locke, John. 




1 


se^ ti!so discourse 


belief, 54 , . .. 




1 


asserlcry^ 57, 60 


empiricism, 121-2 




1 


belief, 47 


inductive arguments, 54 




1 


LUiitext, 125 


knowledge, 33, 91 




1 


empmcai/ieligious, 125-6, 129-30^ 


metaphysics, B5 




1 


148 


ratio nalitJ^ 43, 80, 85 




1 


evidence, 133-4 


reasonablen^iss. 122 




1 


'God-lalk^ 57, 6C)-Z 


logit, 




1 


gramnnaEkal c!ariTy/unci:irity, 


existence of tiod, 6, 34 




1 


114-15 


i logical discourse, 107-S 




1 


Habermas, 206-7 


language^ 124^5 




1 


huTTian life^ 59 


logical formalism, 124, 129^ 142 




1 


intelligibSlily^ 122-3 


togltal positivism^ 




1 


logk, 124-5 


polemical partners, 47 




1 


New Testament, 133 


leligious Eanguage, 48, 123 




1 


Refcrmed EplstemoSogy, 45, 47-S, 


srientism, 122 




1 


56-7 


theologians condemned, 123 




1 


rdfgaou^ gratitude^ 13S 


transcendental meaning denied^ 




1 


symbolism, 12t 


■202 




1 


theiFitic anguage, 62-3 


Vienna school, 122 




1 


WiHgt^nsEein. 16. 44, 47. Ill, 120, 


Loomer, Bernard, 251 




1 


122, 124-7, 133 


love, 25, 174, 286 




1 


WitlgensEeinianism, 47, 59, 6Z-i^ 


Lucas, George, 264 




1 


language games, 


Lucia, Isaac^ Z3 




1 


anaEogy. xvi 


Lufeacs, Georg, 195 




1 


diversityj 129, 141 


Luther, Martin, 17 




1 


evidence, 133 


Lutz-Bachmann, Matthias, xili. 




1 


histoFy, 134 


193-210 




1 


human pride, 140 


Lyotard, J^an-Fran^ois, 164 




1 


identity, 123 






1 


moraJity, 131, 134 


McCarthy. Thomas, IHZ 




1 


overlap, 14S 


McKeon, Richard, 2S1-Z 




1 


posl-secular discourse, 164 


Maimonides Moses ben Maimon], 


22 


1 


religious belief, 1 2 


Malcolm, Norman, 22, 99, 110-12, 




1 


sjieaking ouESiide, 140^ 145 


117, 139-40, 14J-5, 14B 




1 


Lenin, VEadimii Ilyich, 24^ 


Manweiler, Robert, 40 




1 


Levin^. Emmanuel^ 


Marion^ J_-L.. 35j 186 




1 


autonomous sub ect^ 1S9 


Marsden, George, 40^ 51 




1 


Denida, 158, im, 1S6-7. 2S9 


Maix, Karl Frledrich, 




1 


ethacs/religion, 171 


critical of given, 173 




1 


God, 35, 170 


determinate negation. 199 




1 


horror of othetj 173 


dJaEectlcal materialism, 212-13 




1 


Pato, 1S6 


Hegelian philosophy, 197, 201 




1 


postmodernism, 153, 186 


historical materiatism, 193, 2f 1, 




1 


understanding other, 2SR 


205 




1 


vigilant insomnia, 174 


human actions^ I9S 




1 


whoHy other^ 157 


reason, 196 




1 


[iberation Cheoiog}^, 1S7, 26Z-3, 2SK 


Tehgion criticized, 144 




J 





Itidi'x 301 


1 


Marx, Karl Friedrich - c:?utimted 


postmetaphysics, 223-4, 226-9, 246 


1 


setular m^tghE. 6S 


postmodernism, xv 


1 


total itv,2BK 


presence, 16S 


1 


MarxisiTLr 


process metaphysics, 253, 257^ 


1 


atheism, 19B 


259-60, 2^9 


1 


critical theori', 244 


process thouphtj xiv, x^"!, 251-5^ 


1 


dogma^ 198 


262, 266, 268-9. 274-6, 2S4 


1 


Hegel, 19S 


psychicalism, 272-5, 2B4 


1 


niarch of history, 197 


rationalism^ 203 


1 


mateiiaJism, 


realism, 49 


1 


Adorno, 2>5-6 


universal, xv-Kvi 


1 


di!^l^?^:tkal materia i_srti, 212-15 


Whitehead, 17, 271. 27a 


1 


Hegel, 19S 


Wittgenstein, 100, 147, 2B4 


1 


hl5toncal materialism, 195-B, ZOl, 


methodological atheism^ Z30. 235, 


1 


2-(>S^ 


246-7 


1 


Horkheimer. 195-8. 201, 205, 


Mill John Stuait. 121 


1 


212-lS 


Mimamsakas, 26 


1 


Marx, ]9S, 201, 20S, 212^13 


Min, Anselm Kyongsuk, Kiii, 


1 


pragiiaatis.ni, 196 


167-S5 


1 


mathematics, 24 


MitcheU, Basi], Zl 


1 


Mavrodes, George^ 40 


Molina, Luis de, 21-2 


1 


Meland, BeEianJ, 2S1 


Moltmann, Jueigen, 255 


1 


memoiy^ intuttional contentj 53 


Mooie, George ILdivard^ 121 


1 


Menzel. Christopher, 24 


morality, 


1 


Messiah. 161, 1 89 


allegiance, 24 


1 


messiaEitc hope, 169-S3 


discourse, 236 


1 


mei>sianic politics^ 177-9 


justitication, 230 


1 


messianic pD5tmDdernism, 153, 


moral aporia, IBl 


1 


156-62 


moraJ reasoning, ^i3 


1 


messianic time, 171 


religion, 215-16. 230 


1 


meta-epi5temo ogy^ 41, 65 


Wittgenstein, 134 


1 


metaphysics^ 


More, Henry, 22 


1 


Adorno, 2CJ5 


Mulhall, Stephen, xii, xiii, 95-117, 


1 


anti-metaphysics^ 252 


119-21, 124-5, 127, 130, 1^4, 


1 


atheism, 234 


136-7, 139-42 


1 


beliet 34, 100, 146-7 


m>rths, 2tX\ 284 


1 


confusion, 147 




1 


CjitDca] ThtM>r\', xili,, xv 


natura laws, 10-11, 23-4, Sl-2, 33 


1 


DetriiJa, ISti. IBS 


natura theolog}^^ 


1 


disputes criteria, ??5 


abaniJonuient/crilique, 4, 21. 130 


1 


failure, 2(>S 


Catholics, 66 


1 


Habermas, 229 


doxastic merits^ 44 


1 


Hanshorne^ 255. 272-3, 276 


existence of God, 5-14 


1 


Horkheimer. 196, 202 


grammar of faith, 13 L 


1 


Hume, 25 ;^ 


reason, 130-1 


1 


Kant, BS, 20,^,253 


Eheistic reltjijion, 5^, SSL 


1 


Nietzsche, 154. IBB 


negative theolo^, 160, 167-9, 174 


1 


pessimasm, 20^ 


necK-CaBvinism, 41-2, 4b-9, 64, S5 


1 


Plato, 186, 203 


neulra evidence, xil 


J 



302 Judex 




1 


Neiv Testament^ 


modal veisions^ 22 


1 


Epistles see Epis-des 


riantinga, 21-2 


1 


God, 2S9 


prctess thought, 2B4 


1 


historical claanii, 135 


levealed re][^]on. 131 


1 


language, 133 


.51 Anseim^ 34-5, ILO 


1 


parables^ 130 


'liiere is no God', 31, 34 


1 


Nev^Tnan^ John H^nvy, 27^ 82 


traditjona] aFgujnent, 12 


1 


KewEon's Jaivs^ 10 


Whitehead, 271 


1 


Nielsen, Kai, 1C3, 105^7 


Wittgenstein ianism, 1 U) 


1 


Kietzsche, Filedrkh WUhdm, 


ontoiheology, 16H-9 


1 


Christianity, lOfi. 156, 1S6 


oppression, 179, 1K2, 187, 244-5 


1 


ccmpeting basic beliefs^ 9t 


Osiander, Andreas, Bl 


1 


ccrroboratioRr 21? 


other. 


1 


democracy' 156, 186 


horror of other, 173 


1 


DJonysian postmodernEsnij 153-6, 


law of the other, ]5H 


1 


161 


singuJafity, 1K7 


1 


God, 1S4-S 


wholly other sf^ wholly other 


1 


metaphysics, 154, IHS 


without history and society, 167-K5 


1 


perpectivalisBtir 1.S4 




1 


polymorphic plurality, IBS 


pain and suifering, 13^ 23, 1 13-14, Z5S 


1 


secular insight. 65 


Paley, William, 6, 24 


1 


unhealthy iTiriw>chism. 106, 144 


PariFL tj:immune, 33 


1 


non-theistic religions^ analytical 


Pascal, Blaise, 25, 27 


1 


philosopheriir 33 


Passiiaore, John, 277 


1 


Nygren^ A-^ 274 


Paul iee St Paul 


1 




perception, 50, 53, 90 


1 


e8ak£?s, Robert, 23 


persuasion, 2S8, 2S5^6 


1 


Ockham, Wil3ianiof, 22 


pessimism^ 


1 


Ogden, Schuheri M., xly xvl, 266-80 


Enlightenment, 19S 


1 


O'Hara (Father^, lOT 


Horkl-ieimer, 198, 201-4, 213, 244 


1 


Old Testamenlr 


metaphysics. 203 


1 


see tiiso Bible 


^repticism, 203 


1 


Abraham, 15S, 163, 179 


Schopenhauer, 198, 201, Z03, 


1 


Babe]. 164-5 


205-6, 244 


1 


Exodus, 135 


Eharisfi's, 146 


1 


Genes-is, 12 


PhJIlipi D-Z , 


1 


historical claims, 135 


introduction, xi-xvia 


1 


Isaiah, 157 


voices in discussion, 31-6, S5-92, 


1 


Leviticus, l[}5 


144-5tl, Jfi6-9(>, Z44-a, ZHl-90 


1 


prophets^ 133 


Wittgensteinianiam, 16, 44-6, 


1 


Psa ms, 57 


57-62, 103-6, 110-11 


1 


scapegoat rlte^ lOS-6 


philosophical theoSogy, 


1 


'Siiaddai', 25^ 


apologetic arguments, 24-6, 33 


1 


Wisdom of Solomon, 3 


contemporary tS^rust, 23-4 


1 


Olympian height, xiv, 2S1 


disrussioii, 31-6 


1 


ontologlcaB aFKLiment^, 


limits, 25 


1 


analytical pliilosophy, 5^ 35 


philosophical ttiiCism, 1^20 


1 


tmparilaL reason, 31 


revival, 21 


1 


logical necessity, 6 


theistic doctrines/proofs, 23-4 


J 





Itidi'x i03 


1 


phiEasophy. 


logical positivism, 47 


1 


analytical phiiosophcrs, 14, 16-17^ 


Refojmed EpSst'Emolog>^, 47, 66, 76 


1 


22, 31^ 


Wittgenstein, 47 


1 


dis^iptinary bcundarles, 261 


politics. 


1 


e>Llstentia( questions^ xlv, 26S-9 


communfity^ IHi 


1 


nature of phUosophy. \\-xu 


deconstmction, 178 


1 


positivism, i;^. 194 


democracy, 156, 172-3, 177, 179, 


1 


science^ 269 


La6 ' 


1 


tdsk^, ZS3i 


messianic, 177-9' 


1 


Pike, N€lson, 22 


oppression. 179, 1S2, iS7 


1 


Plajitinga, Alvin^ 


positivEsm, 


1 


analytic phi3osophy, 14 


5^€ iiho logical po5]ti%ism 


1 


depth of ingression^ 46 


Adorno, 200-1 


1 


Doxastic Ideal^ 56 


HorkheJmer, 194, 2i:]0-l 


1 


epistemolcigy from btloiv. 57 


pluEosophv, 13, L94 


1 


evidence, 2Z, 66, 76^7, S6 


science, 200-1 


1 


externalism, ao 


post-stmcturaiLsm^ 1S6 


1 


Faiti^ cmci Rath^hjiity\ ]4-15. 40. 42, 


post metaphysics.. 223-4, 226-9, 246 


1 


46, 5(3^1, 6b, HS, H7 


post modern EsiTi, 


1 


foundataonalfsm^ 87 


conver^nces^ 163-5 


1 


G{}ii ami Other Mira^-V 4t>-l 


deconsrmction nee deconstniction 


1 


logkaE positivism, 4S 


Deirida .se^' Derrid a, Jacques 


1 


mela-epistemolojv, 65 


difference, 153^, 156-7 


1 


onEolrjgical arguments. Z1.-2 


Dionysian version, 15:]?-9^ 161 


1 


perception^ SO 


discourse^ 164-5 


1 


process thought, 264 


Horkheimer. 199 


1 


proper[y baiiic belief, 45, 86^-3 


identity^ 173 


1 


rationaiity-evidenEialisni^ 70-L 


Kierkegaard, 153, 156 


1 


Reids influence^ 49 


messianic postmodernism, 153-66 


1 


warrant theory^ 15, 51-2, 56^ 77 


metaphysics, xv 


1 


rfato. 


Nietzsche, 15 3-6, 161 


1 


antecedent judgennents, S2 


process thought^ 263 


1 


CQTiteniptationK 9<> 


Reformed Epi5teitJolog>^, 4K 


1 


Demiurge, ^ 


rival programmes, J7-1S 


1 


goodness, '^, 156 


truth. 17-L8 


1 


ideally formeJ hehef, S3 


univeriaJ reason, xiii 


1 


metaphysics, 1S6, 203 


pragmatism. 


1 


Farmtnitk^s, 153 


corrohoralion iSewiUsningXf 218-19 


1 


reality, xiv, xv 


deconstniction, 182 


1 


Sifphist, 158 


historical materiaJiism. 196 


1 


traditional ideologaes, 173 


realism, 227 


1 


plausibitity structures^ 35 


truth, IB7, 224, 228, 231-2, 245 


1 


PEoUnus. 60-lj 157 


prayer, 


1 


plura ism, 


contemplation, 26 


1 


doxastic merit:^. 4^, 6S 


intelligibility, 105 


1 


polymorphic, 1K6 


whollv oth-er. 170 


1 


Reformed Epistemology, 65 


predictions. 131-3 


1 


polemical partners^ 


prescriptive revisionism, 110 


1 


evidentialism, 66, 76 


presence, 53, 16R-9 


J 



304 Imii^x 




1 


PreivnaaticSj Kiv^ 2R4 


transdisciplinarv^ 26 1 


1 


probability, 


ukamate reality xiv 


1 


antecedejiE ju^ements^ 32 


Wittgensteinianism, 264, 268 


1 


aigumients, efficacy, xii 


proper function ing^ nonnative 


1 


beheJ, xii, sv, 7-11, U-M, 25, ^2, 


notion. XV 


1 


97, 122 


Protestants, existence of God, 4 


1 


€X3zt values, 7 


Prozesky, Martin, 27 H 


1 


predJctJDns, Ki2 


psychicalism, 272-5, 284 


1 


scientists, iM^ 


p^chological anthropology, .197 


1 


suffKient, .15 


Puritans, 32 


1 


trust in GoJ, xv 




1 


process t iciught, 


Quantum Theory, 7 


1 


causality^ 2SB, 2^1 


Quran, 26 


1 


ccsmology, 2.St-2, 261-3, Z68 




1 


deconstmction, 263 


Kabner, Kar, 175 


1 


determinism. 2S7 


ratio naiity, 


1 


discDursEr xiv 


belief, xii, 15^ 34-5 


1 


discussion^ 2K1-7 


doxastic merits. SB 

r + 


1 


divine mutabLLiiv, 254 


tnligitenmcnt, xal. 43, 153^ 177 


1 


diviQeomnipolencer 258-9^ 267^ 


immediate belief. 44 


1 


269-7t> 


inference, 56 


1 


divine omniscience, 256-7^ 2S9, 


intellectuat duiry, 69 


1 


267 


justlfjcation^ 75 


1 


empiricism, 251, 263-9 


modernism, 153 


1 


ethics, 2R4 


rational grounding. 43, 4S, 56 


1 


existential questions, xfv, xvl. 


Reformied Epistemology, xii, 15-16, 


1 


26K-9, 278 


43, BS 


1 


experience, 272-.3 


warrant theory, 15-15, 75 


1 


raith, 252 


Ratzch, Del, 23 


1 


femmism. 262-3, 2fi7 


HawEs, John^ 145 


1 


God, 2S4-9, 269-75 


realis-m, 


1 


liberation Iheologj^, 262-3 


metaphysics, 49 


1 


itietaphysics, xiv, xvi, 251-5, 262, 


pragmatism, 227 


1 


266, 26J^9, 274-6, 2S4 


reality^ 


1 


neo-naturaitsm. 251, 268 


God, xiv, xvi, S9 


1 


ontologlca argunnents, 2.B4 


PlatOj xiv, XV 


1 


Plantinga, 264 


process thought, xiv 


1 


postiisoderni&jn, 263 


Retormed Epistemology, xvi 


1 


practice, 26 1 


ultimate reality, xiv, xvi 


1 


process metaphysics, 253, 257^ 


understanding reality 2S2 


1 


2S9-60, 269 


reason, 


H 


psychicalism, 272-S, 284 


Aristotle^ ji3 


1 


Reformed EpisTcmo3ogy, 264-5 


CiSticai Theory, 163 


1 


lesponse to Cobb, 266-SO 


Horkheinner, 196, 207 


1 


rival programmes, 17 


Kierkegaard, 164 


1 


social location^ 262 


Marx, 196 


1 


substance, 1 7 


natural theoiogy, 130-1 


1 


suffering, 255 


ontoiogicaS arguanents, 31 


1 


theo3ogy, 252, 261, 266, ZH4 


postmodernism, xiii 


J 





Itidi'x 305 


1 


leasonabEeness. 


determinate, 177 


1 


belief, 127-S, ;^0 


ethics, 171 


1 


Christianky, 122 


Ciod st?e God 


1 


predictions^ 1 32 


Hinduism, 26, 256 


1 


Wittgenstein, 1Z7-B, 130, 132 


Horkheimei, 193, 197-S, 212-16, 


1 


reasons^ 


229-30 


1 


belief, 4:i-i 


Jemsh .^i^f Judaism 


1 


evidence^ 97-B 


Maix, 144 


1 


lecognitionj, 147-S 


messianic hope, 169-SJl 


1 


Reformed Epistemologj'^ 


morality, ZI5-16, 230 


1 


analytical philosophy, 15 


non-theistic, 33 


1 


ba^icali^ts, 66-7 


rationally grounded religion. 4,% 


1 


belief 5ee basic belief 


B5, 172 


1 


bitiadiv undersloodr 42 


religion without religion, 15R-9, 


1 


dis-cassioRj HS-92 


174, 176, 1B7, 189-90 


1 


foundational ism, 7&, S7 


revealed, 131 


1 


InfeFence. 76-9, S6 


semantic contents, 229-31 


1 


language, 45, 47-S, 56-7 


soctal contribution, 212-15 


1 


meta-epistemology'^ 41 


Iheastic, 5, 22. '^-^, 65-6. Ji2 


1 


nanowly understood. 42-3. 45-6, 


unhealthy masochism, 106, 144 


1 


50 


who 3v other 169 


1 


objections, 65-6 


Wittgenstein, x.iL, 16, 46-7, 95-117, 


1 


origins^ 39-40 


1 19^3 


1 


rlanringa si-'f rlanrinRar Alvin 


WitTgensteinlanism, _xii3, 16, SS, 


1 


pSurahsm, 65 


103, 108, 144 


1 


polemica] partners, 47, 66, 76 


re Lgious ant hroiic logy. 50. 56 


1 


postmodernism, 4S 


re igious aucliority, 90-1 


1 


pre-histor}^^ 40-1, 85 


re igious belief see belief 


1 


process thought^ Z64-S 


reiigious controversies^ 9S, HI9 


1 


rationality, xii,, 15-16^ 431, S5 


re igious dogmatism, 44 


1 


reality^ x\1 


re igious experience, x\% 31 


1 


ReforniL'il /f2iiniat, 87 


religious faith sec Taith 


1 


religinu^ dogmatism, 44 


religious platitude, 138 


1 


religious expenence, xv 


re igious knowing, 65 


1 


religious p lilosophy. 54-5 


re igious philosophy 64-5 


1 


Tix-sl pfngrammes, 14-16 


re igious ritu;i1, IClft, 110 


1 


uttlity, 15 


religious trath, 231-7j 245 


1 


^VJltgensteinianisiii distinguished _r 


Rescher, Nicholas, ] 64 


1 


4a-9, 5B, 61-2, 85-6, H8 


Rhees, Rush, x\% B8-9, 129-30 


1 


Reformed-Piesbyterian tradition. 41 


risk, non-existence of God, 11-12, 25 


1 


Reid, Thomas, 49-50, 55-7, 72, 76, 


Rorty, RjchaTd. 156, 189,224 


1 


82. SS, 90 


Rowe, William, 23 


1 


Mtigion, 


Russrli, Eeruand, 120-1 


1 


see also theism 




1 


anthropology, 5C, 56 


sacrifice, obhgations, 179-80 


1 


Buddhism, 256, 260, 275, 2S3, 2SS 


St Anselm see AnseEm 


1 


Christian see Christianity 


St Augustine sef Augustine of Hippo 


1 


Critical Theory, 193-24S 


St Francis of j\ssist, 14S ' 


1 


Deirida, 158, 169-83, 187, 1S9-90 


St Irenaeus, 17 


J 



306 Jjet/fJt 




1 


St Paul, 


Socrates, 114, 164, 2S6 


1 


belief, 12 


Sokal, Alan, 155^6 


1 


Chrastaanlty, 17 


^nui. substance, 17, 104 


1 


docCrmal falsityr J46 


Special K, 75, 79 


1 


Epistles iee Episiles 


Stalin, Joseph, 19S 


1 


'mvis!bEe things' of Gotf, H 


Stump, Eleonore, 21 


1 


natural] theoJogy, H2 


suffering and pain, 13,23, 113-14, 


1 


wis-dom, 12K 


255 


1 


St Thomas see Aquinas, Thomas 


super-facts, discourse, xv\ 


1 


sca].iegoat ritCj lOS-6 


superstition, 104, 106-7, 109-10, 


1 


sceptitism^ 


146 


1 


deconstmctioax. I4S. I8Z 


Swinburn-e^, Richard, xli, xv, ^-21, 2.3, 


1 


eplstemology, 201-2, 205 


25^,91 


1 


Horkheimer, 201-5, 244 




1 


Hume, IZZ 


TayEor. MarkC-, 155 


1 


pessimism, 203 


teleoiogicaE argument, 131 


1 


sin, ]40, 145, 147 


Thales, 2i^4 


1 


Scheler, Max, 194 


thcismj 


1 


Stlilei-etmacher^ FriedrJch, 24 


scff tiho God 


1 


scholastics, 21 


analytical pJiiiosophy, 22, 65 


1 


Schopenhauer, Arthur, 19K, 201, 203^ 


Christianity, 55 


1 


205-6, 244 


doctrines/proofs, 2'^4 


1 


science, 


Hartshorne, 264 


1 


rvewton'i Jaws, 10 


Hume, 12 


1 


philosophy, 269 


language, 62-3 


1 


positivism, 200-1 


naEura] theology, 5, 82 


1 


posEniCMlernisnfi, 1 55-6 


philosophical theology, ]-20 


1 


probaL>i;illy^ i^'A 


Teligions, 5, 22^ 31^, 65-6, S2 


1 


Quantum Theory, 7 


St Thomas Aquinas^ 4^ 22 


1 


scientism, 122 


theology. 


1 


Whitehead, xiv, 282 


btack theo]og>; 287 


1 


S€afle,John, 164, IKS 


Christian see Christian theologians 


1 


secular hopes, better world, xiii 


discouf se^ 235 


1 


seeing, taith, xv 


liberation theolog}^, 187, 262-S, 2B8 


1 


self-lnteiesE, goodness, 11, 25 


natural see natural theology 


1 


sensations, 50, 90 


negative theology, 160, 167-9, 174 


1 


' SilesiuSj Angelus, 1 60 


ontotheology, 168-9 


1 


simplicity. 


philosophicaS stv philosophical 


1 


disposition. Bl 


theology 


1 


divine simpEtcitVr 42 


Wittgenstein. 131-7 


1 


plau5ibilaty, ^^5 


Tillich, Paul Johannes, 60, 175, 204, 


1 


sinfuEne:>s, 


271, 275 


1 


divine covenant^ 13J-J 


totalitarian oppiesyon, 179^ 1B2 


1 


fieedom from sin, 106 


totalities. 


1 


human disposition, 116 


deconstniction, 167, 1B2 


1 


Original Sin, 117, 140, 145 


Identity. 1S7 


1 


scepticism, 140, 145, 147 


liberation theo3og)v 288 


1 


singuiaFir>', 170-1, 179, 18Z, 1S7 


Trinity, Z3, 283 


1 


Siva, 26 


tnisl, xv^ 49 


J 





Itui^x 307 


1 


truthj 


creativity, 256, 271 


1 


CiUicaJ Theory, 211 . 


criticism of abstractions, 26S 


1 


Habeimas, XEii, 207-S, 221, 224-7, 


deconstniction, 26J-5 


1 


23 1-7, 245, Zfi9 


diiine muEabilitj', 254 


1 


Horkheimei, 196, 20:i-4, 213-Zl, 


experience, 272-3 


1 


225^, 23] 


God, 255-6, 270-1 


1 


'Janus-face', 225, 232 


metaphysics, 17, 271, 278 


1 


postmodernism, 17^ IS 


ontological arguiTientSj 271 


1 


pragmatism, 187^ 224^ 22S, 231-2^ 


physical prehensions, 253, 25£ii^ 272 


1 


245 

+ 


process thought^ 251. 266 


1 


Kllgious truth, 231-7, 245 


science, xiy 2S2 


1 


truth-relevant merirs, 42-3 


specu]ative phi cisrsphy, 282 


1 


unconditionaJity. 22S-6 


whol3y othcr^ 


1 


Wjltgejisleinianisiiiy 146 


sff also oth^r 
deco]"istmction, 161 


1 


Udayana, 26 


determinacy 171. 176 


1 


ultimate rea ity, process thought, xiv 


God, 169-70, 1B6 


1 


universe^ 


hospitality, 162 


1 


beauty 9-10 


messianic, 177 


1 


large hypothesis, 13-14 


negative theology", 168, 174 


1 


natural laws, ]f)-ll 


paradox, 157 


1 


unobser\'able causes, 13 


prayer, 170 


1 


utopianism^ 221-2, 245 


religion, 169 


1 


d'n''"Vi 


Wieman, Henry Nelson, 251, 2S2 


1 


Vedanta^ 256 


Winch, Peter, 8S, 111-15, 117, 124, 


1 


Vedas, 26 


140, 145, 148 


1 


virtue. 


wisdom, 12K, 2K3 


1 


faith, 11, 25 


wise men, 34, 128 


1 


warranted beSlef^ 27 


Winsenschaflsiebre, 51, 5?^ 
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 


1 


Wainwright, WlMlamJ_, xii, xv, 21-30 


beEtef, 44, 46-7, lGO-2, 127-8, 


1 


warrant theory^ 


13Ei^9 


1 


basic belinf^ 45, 77 


Biblical texl: misunderstood, 127-S 


1 


cognitive fatilities, IS 


Rtuc and Bro\\'n Boaki, 12? 


1 


DoxastEC Ideal, 56 


Christianity, 1:^2-4, 137 


1 


entir ementj 73 


commitmenE, 100 


1 


evidence^ 86 


contemplation, 9i> 


1 


evldentiaJisiit, 7.-^-^ 


Citttitre ami Vahit^, 96, 9S, 100, 137 


1 


p]i]l<jsc"jphical actounts^ 13^ 51-2 


difference, kv. 188, 246 


1 


TaEionaiit^', 15-16, 75 


discussion, 144-50 


1 


reliabihst theories, 7'A 


eariy views, xiil. 120 


1 


virtue, 27 


i'ltie ExhtenZj 99-100 


1 


Way of Edeas theorists, 50 


cpistemology, 120 


1 


Weil, Simone, 17 


existence of God, 9R-101 


1 


Welch, Sharon, 155 


intelligibihty, 122^^, 130 


1 


Weston, Michael, 1S8 


interpretation of religion, 96-103 


1 


Whitehead, AlfrudNorth^ 


know3*:dge, 115-16, 120-1 


1 


causahty 258 


language, 15, 4^, 47, 111, 120. 122, 


1 


cosmology, 252 


124-7 


J 



?t08 Imii^x 




1 


Witlgenstein, Ludwig - ■fONtTFJUfrf 


Tjod-^talk^ 57, 60-2 


1 


Lecturer and Couwi'sati^u^, 96-7. 99> 


human life, 59 


1 


124-9, 131-4, 144-7 


interpretation of reJagion, 103-1 L 


1 


login, L20-1, 128-9 


language, 47, 59, 6Z-3 


1 


logical positivism^ 4/ 


language gaaites see language 


1 


metaphy-sics, 1(K>, 147, 284 


games 


1 


morality, \??4, 140 


methodology. 95 


1 


0}2 Certamty, 46-7, BB, 129 


ontoiogica^ aigumentSj 1 10 


1 


philosophers, 90 


Phillips, 16,44^, 57^2, 103-6, 


1 


riuiosopiiiait Im'esti^atiofis, MZ, 


11(3-11 


1 


125-7, 129-31, 133-4, 141, 147 


phi osophy of rehRion, 58 


1 


pictures, 99, 107 


process fhouglit, 264, 26K 


1 


polemical partner, 47 


lefertln^ toGod, SH 


1 


predictions, 3^^1-3 


Reformed Episteniology 


1 


psycholGgjr^ 120 


distinguis led, 4K^9, 5S, 61-Z, 


1 


feasonableaiess, 127-8, U(J, 132 


a5^, 81i 


1 


Reroihctions cfWittgensteifi, 96 


TeLigion Immune to criticism, xiii^ 


1 


religioEi. xii, 16, 46-7, 9S-117^ 


103, i08, 144 


1 


119^3 


Tival programmes, 16-17 


1 


TCttgious contepEs, 97 


self-contained religion, 16 


1 


leMgious interpretations, 111-17 


superstition, 104, 106-7, 109-10 


1 


fesponse to MulhaJI, 119-43 


the] Stic languLige, 62-3 


1 


spiritual fervour, 1 1 1 


truth/falsicy, 146 


1 


taken foi grant-ed, 47 


worship^ 59 


1 


theoJogVr 131-7 


Wcllerstorff. Nicholas, scil, 14, 39-63, 


1 


rmifr^ffcd.s. 122, 125-7, 129, l?ll. 


64^, 68, 73, 78-80 


1 


137, 141, 145, 147 


Wood, Jay, 27 


1 


wisdom of the wise, 12a 


worship. Wattgensteinlanisnij 59 


1 


Wittgenstein ianism, 


Wykstra, Stephen, xii, ^9, 64-B4 


1 


atheism, 4S, fiS 


Wynn, Mark. 14 


1 


belief, 47 




1 


Christianity, 16, 103, i06 


Yankelevitch, VJadimar, 157 


1 


ccnteiciplative character, xii, xiv 




1 


discourse, xvi 


Zagzetaski, Linda, 27 


1 


fideism, 16, 103, 108, 125, 130-1, 


ZaraEhustra, 161 


1 


144 


Zen, 256 


J 



JoimD. Capiito 161 

'the impossible^ The impossible Is to be distinguished from the ^possi- 
ble', which means lor lilm the 'relatively' othcr^ ivh^iL Is no move Lhan 
3 new move in an old Ramc, the future that 15 foreseeable, plannable, 
programmable- Deconstruetion is the affirmation of the 'wliolly oilier^ 
of a new ^mc altogether, of an unforeseeable surprise, in virtue of 
which ibe current order is kept in principle 'open^ or ■'deconstmcttble'. 
To the coming of tiiis wholly othcr^ wc say 'yes', and 'yes' again^ oui, 
oui, since every yes demands a follow throuj^h which keeps its hands to 
tlie ptougli, lest the resolve slacken or the repetition become rote. 
Deconstruetion says yes to Tifsventhn de i'iiiiire\ where hiventiofi should 
not be translated as 'Invention', which would surest the Dionysian 
play of Nictzsehean fictions, but tendered tather in messianic terms, as 
the 1n-com1ng of the others in keeping with its Latin roots, uf-veiiiem. 
In the military if someone shouts 'incoming', everyone heads tor cover. 
But, in messianic postmodernism to shout ^incoming' is to proclaim 
the good news, which Is why the proper response 10 the incoming, and 
the first, last and constant prayer of deconstruetion, is to shout, to 
pray, 'viej^-f, i?ur, oul'. 

According to an old rabbinical story that Derrida finds Iq Bianchot, 
the Messiah never arrives. His vtry meaning is to be always^ structurally 
to come, a ve}isf, so that if he ever showed up, ever actuaHy appeared, he 
would ruin everylhing.^^^ The coming (Vi.'j»it^) of the Mcssiaii, lilanchot 
said, must never be confused with his actual presence (presence). 
Indeed^ if one day he did show up incognito, we w-ould ask hiin 'When 
will you come?' The coming of the Messiah belongs to what Derrida 
calls the ^absolulc^ future, the future which is structurally futural, 
always to come^ hot the future present, the future that will roll around 
into presence sooner or later. For If the Messiah ever came into tiie 
present, history would close and we would have no more futuie, no 
more hope. What would there be left to come? {to adapt Zaratliustra's 
complaint). Even in Christianity, which from the point of view of the 
rabbis is too impalient^ wheie It is believed that the Messiah actually 
did come, everyone now^ wants to know, 'when will he come again?' 
For it belotigs to the very idea of the future^ of hopc^ of historyn that the 
>v^essiah is still to cof^e. Furthermore, and this is a point of great impor- 
tance for Derrida^ if the Messiah were actually to come, to become pre- 
sent, a war would surely break out over what language he spoke, what 
nation he visited^ where his capital is to be ii^slalledn who is to be his 
vicar and hold his ke^^, who is authorized to speak In his name, who is 
authorized to say wliat he said and what he meant, or to translate it into 



162 Phihsnphy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

Other languages, and who has the power to exclude and excommunicate 
those who disagree with (he authorized interpretation of what he said. 
(If the absolute truth ever amvedj who could he trusted with it?). 

The affirnialion of llie iii-coming of the wholly other, Derrida will 
now sa^j is the affirmation of the 'justice' tocomCj where justice has the 
sense not of a Greek universal hut of the justice due lo the 'singutar' 
qhEh to the one whose every tear and every hair has been counted by 
God, to the outcast, the outsider, the 'widow, the orphan, and the 
stranger'j to use the biblical figure that Levinas invokes. In deconstruct 
tioiij the 'kingdom of God' would be a kingdom of nobodies^ of what 
t*au! called hi me o^ta. The point of Etenida's messianic is to hold the 
present up against the white light of absolute future, of absolute justice, 
which means the justice which is ahvays to come, wliich prevents the 
present order from closing over on itself and declaring itself just, or well 
on the way to justice, in a perfidious asymptotic progress that tolerates 
an intolerable amount of misery."^ The affirmation of justice in decon- 
struction is the affirmation of 'hospitality' to the other, of making the 
other welcome. LSut to offer hospitality to the 'wholly other' is to 
expose yourself to a 'surprise', to being overtaken by what you did not 
see comings to get more than you bargained foi, since liospitality is not 
supposed to be a bargain but a gift. The notion of hospitality puts a 
stress on the idea of a 'community^ which on one etymology means 
com-mtmir^, to butM a defence (miimre) around (com) oneself, lo protect 
oneself against the other Tliat is the very opposite of deconstruction 
whose very idea is to make the other welcome, the wholly other, the 
other whom I cannot circumscritae in advance by preconditions. Uut 
liow can one welcome the other 'unconditionally'? Are we to open the 
banquet to every passer-by? Whoever heard of such a thing? But then 
againj how could one he conditioiiatly hospitable, 'welcoming^ only 
those wliom one has carefully chosen in advance and only subject to 
certain conditions? Tliac is not a true welcoming but a closing off, a pri- 
vate list, a closed circle of Invitees. Conditional hospitality is as incoher- 
ent as conditional love, as loving someone but only up to a point, after 
which w^e lose interest. 

Thus, far from being a philosophy of despair, as its critics claim, this 
form of postmodernism turns on messianic hope ivictis). Far from l^Ncing 
nihihstic, it is deeply affirmative, otii, out Far from being rclativistlc and 
capricious, it insists upon the uncircumventable responsibility of the 
subject to the other From reducing everything to subjectivistic play of 
traces or sigtiifiers, it is organized around alterity, indeed around the 
wholly other. 



foSmD. Caputo 163 



A problem 



The largest sticking pointy the main difficulty, ivhich racssmnic post- 
modernism poses to 'the philosophy of religion' has to do with Dcrrida's 
intractable suspicion of what he calls the 'eoncjetc messianisms\ the 
historical religions of the Book, which on Dcrrlda's account have a his- 
tory of violence built righl into them. The power ol" the messianic on 
Derrida's accounling is precisely its indeterminacy, Its structural emptl- 
nesSj the resistance it puts up against Ihe closure of the present or 
prevailing orders that blocks off in advance any claims of exclusivity on 
the part of any religion or of any determinate body of dogmatic claims 
that may take itself to be tise icvcalcd word of God. As an Algerian 
(Arab) Jew- who speaks (Christian Latin) French, Elerrida ts deeply 
impressed by the capacity of the reli^ons of the Book to wage war on 
one another, on the ability of the children of Abraham to slaughter one 
another tn the name of God. If his disUnction between Ihe concrete 
messlanlsms and the formal messianic does not mduce to a dlstLncllon 
bctw^een war and peace^ that is at least an important part of its import. 
The ;.»'H possible, the justice to noma, precludes in advance che claim of 
any confession or any tradition to exclusive or definitive truth. One 
needs Lo proceed witli caution here. On the one hand^ one needs to 
avoid dismissive gestures that would ignore the pow='erful force for jus- 
tice that stirs w^itliln the concrete iiicssianisms, a force that nourished 
Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Martin Luther Kin^, and Dorothy Day and count- 
less otlierSn famous and unknown alike. On the olher hand^ such wit- 
nessing strengthens faith, but it does not pass over ii^to knowledge^ 
because people can witness with their lives and deaths to entirely 
different things. In a deconstructlve philosophy of religion, the con- 
crete messianisms might be tmique but never exdusive or defiifitlw, each 
longing and sighing in its own way for the tout uutre, each praying and 
weeping in its own way over the name of God. Bui none of them is 
relieved of the need to ask^ without having a secret answer up its 
sleeve^ ^md f^tj iutm, cum liettm meum umo? 



Convergences 



The line of thought that runs through this second^ messianic version of 
posttnodernism converges with other approaches on at leasl tw^o points. 

(1) Postmodernism does not reject reason^ as Us critics charge^ but 
rather, like critical theory, postmodernism has redescritKd ^reason' in 



164 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

intcrsub|ccHvc terms. Reason in postmodcrntsm is not a subject- 
object iclationship enacted within the solilaryj nionological confines 
of a 'pure' reason, whose very purity removes it from history, lan^age 
and the human community. Rallicr^ like critical theory^ 'reason^ for 
posmiodcrnists ts a relationship of spcakinj; subject with speaking 
subject and so reason has the sense of 'reasoning together^ But by 
rejecting the solitary ahistorical subject^ postmo-dernhniH unlike critical 
theorists^ go on to reject the Tmnscemk'tit^iU^m of liabermas's notion of 
communicative rationalit)', the notion that intersubjective communi- 
cation is guided from wiihin by ahistorical laws of rationality, which 
it regards as just so much ahistorical modernism or neo- Kantianism. 
Furthermore^ postmodernists regard consensus not as the goal of 
communicationj but simply as a temporary pause in the conversation- 
Otherwise, the goal of communication would be silence. Were every- 
ojic saying the same thing, there would be no reason to say an^^^hing. 
The idea behind the multiplication of voices - chc story of Babel - can 
liardly be to speak nfin \^oce, for where there is one voice there is no 
voicCj where there is only one mterpretationj no interpretation is 
allowed. The idea of ^reason' that is astir in postmodernism turns on 
the idea Ihat the hiti^uage of the wholly other is the lan^age of the 
whoUy other, that Iho wholly other always offers a surprise. These words 
come to me from the other shore; they arc not my words^ not some- 
tiling 1 already know in principle. The idea of reason in postmod- 
ernism is deeply opposed to any version, direct or indirect^ of Socratic 
tmijeiitks, but rather, like Kierkegaard, it turns on the model of the 
teacher, the one wlio comes over me with something 1 do not know, so 
tiiat reason means learning how to welcome the wholly othcr^ and rea- 
son is a form of hospitality.^- 

(2) The attempt to open up a post-secular discourse, to repeat or 
rcinstitute religion in a post-critical or post-modern way to re-establish 
the rights of religious discourse after modernist critiques have run 
their course, is closely tied up with the notion of laaiguage games ii:L 
Wittgenstim. That claim is documcntable in Derrida^s early interest 
in Austin, which Scarle uttcfly confounds^ and It Is quite exphcit In 
Lyotard. who makes extensive use of \\^ittgen stein in The Post7t\0{ieni 
CamUthfi, fast dmung, and The Different I'he point is plain. Religious 
discourse is another and irreducible way to think and speak, religtous 
practices anotherj irreducible way to tx^. Postmodernism resists mightily 
the hegemony of o^'crarchlng discourses or metalanguages into ■which 
other discourses are to be assimilated, reduced^ or translated without 
remainder. Postmodernists are committed to the irreducible plurality of 



foSmD. Caputo 165 

discursive practices and rules^ and they resist at c^'ciy turn (he notion 
that there is a privileged access to ihc things tiictiisclves that is the 
exclusive province of a particular discipline, natural language, iTaditlon^ 
mysLical experience, or religious faith^ which is why in postmodernism 
'religious discourse' itself refers to a plurality of language games, to 
many dilferenl traditions, saying many different things. Postmodernists 
think that there are many way^ for tilings to be and many ways to 
speak- The story of the lower of Babel is one of their favourite biblical 
narratives, putting God^ as it does^ on tiic side of the deconstructors of 
tall towers^ monolingualismj and univocity. 

in tiie end, to come bacl^ to my initial distinction between Dionysian 
and messianic postmodernism^ one would not gel things right until 
one could see the porousness of this distmctionn the way these two 

bleed into and coniniunicate with each olher^ the way if I niay say so^ 
the postmodern religious sage would have to take the impudent form 
of a Dionysian rabbi- 



Notes 



1. Mark C- Taylor and Jose Marquez, 7>]f K^at: Lais Vegas^ NV. A CD-ROM. 
(Chicago: University of ChEcago Viesf^, 1998]_ 

2_ Cambrklge: Harvard University Pres5^ 199S. 

3- Brian Ingiattla, Pa'itniOiieni Theory iuict Bihiicai Theijh^' (C^ainbriJgeL Cam- 
bridge University Press^ 1995 >_ Conlrarv' lo hi^ title^ Ingraiha presents us with 
a rigorous either/or: eittier poslniodem theory or biblical theoSogy, but no 
mBKin^! His criticisms of Derrida make the staaidard mistake cf assimiEjiting 
Derricia to Nietzschean postmodernism and mining Derrida's 'messianic' side. 

4. Emmanuel Levinas, Totniiity an^i I^ifjtiityt trans. A_ Lingis (Pittsburgh: 
Duque'ine UniversEty Press, 19S93, p. 64_ 

5_ Jacques Derrida, The Gift of Detiti}, iran:^- David Wilb (Chicago: University of 
Chicago Press, 1995], p. 49. 

6_ In these thinkers both premodem religious, and postmodern themes are 
made to Intermingle in a fascinatrng way. an intermingling aptly captured by 
the phrase 'post-secuEar'. Post-secuiar thinking rejecis the narrow, abstract 
and ahistorical concept of rationality put forth by the Enlighteaiment^ and in 
particular the reduclionistic tendencies of Enlightenment rationality. TotaJiz- 
ing. elaminationist^ reduction istic critiques of leltgkon, whether based upo]i 
the universal sweep of physics i naturalisml. econonnics (Marji), or the uncon- 
scious (freudlj are just more tentacles of th^ Aufkiciruti,^ 'rying to consume 
everything on its plate. 

7. At this point T am only adumbrating an argument de^^^d[oped in detail in 
John D- Caputo, Tiie Prayers nmi Tet^rs of JiWi^m's Derriihi: Reil^io!} wittioiil 



166 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

Rt'ii^^Um (Bloomington: Tndiana Univeisity Press^ I???]; foi a correlative but 
more mtrnrMluctory s-tudy to the lat-er Derrida, which is where these religious 
thematics aie to be founds see /Jfro?f5tn/4."Ceflj? j>] n \htt*^fir^U! ti ('om'ersntii^n 
with factju^i D^niiiii, edited with £k comnii^ntary by John D_ Caputo iNew 
Yoik: Fofdham Unaversity Press, 1997J. 

K. 5£'f Jacques Durrtda and Geoffrey Bennin^on, Jiici^ies Dcrmlu, trans. Geoffrey 
KL']:iniiTigton (Chicago! University of Chicago Press^ 1993.1^ pp. IS^^S. Tor a 
lengthier commentary an Circonfessiou, 5^ my Prayers lij?J Te^irs of J{icijues 
D]frrkt€if VI, 'CQnfession\ To this pcstrriodern interest in Augustine should 
be added the work of the lare Jean-Framfois l.yotard, who at the tir:ie of liis 
death was writing a lx>ok about St Augustin-e's Confe.'i.-iWiss, the work of the 
ILiigtish theologian John Mtthank, and the recent publication in the (ii^:uws' 
tnii.'s^abt of Heidegger's 1920-21 lectures on the Lett£rs to the Tiiessah^iitins 
and the Tenth Book of the CGufessian^f commentaries which 9ie at the heart 
of the 'genesis' ot Heiug (\ntl T!n?e. 

9. iVf Caputo, Ttie P^aj.'en iimi Tea^s offac^jues Derrudu^ 1^ The Apophatic\ 

10. See NsitiMi, pp. 24^5, 156-SO. 

11- T3ial is the argument of Specters ofK-Iarx fKew York^ Routledge, 1 994 J against 
the liberal euphoria of the new world order, invoking the :>pectre of Marx. Ln 
messianic terms thai go back to Waiter benjamin. 

12- See Levinas, Totaiity ami Infinity, pp. ZOl-4, 216-19, 252. 



11 

The Other without History and 
Society - a Dialogue with Derrida 



Let mc begin by congraiulaling Professor Capuco for his very lucid pre- 
sentation of postmodernism and its potential as a f philosophy of religion. 
I also want to thank him for writing two very helpful hiLioduc Lions and 
commentaries on Derrida, Decofistivction in a Nut^ht'H: a Conversation witli 
fiiafiics Demdti and The Fmycrs lusti Ttws of Jciajues Desmhi: KcU^hu witlscut 
Reli^^ion^ Pnjyers and Teiirs, espccia^y, is a masterpiece of exposition. 
anal)^is^ andcomposilion, which 1 would erilhusiaslically recommend lo 
aU students of Derrida. So much of what lie says in the paper presupposes 
his much more elaborate and exleiisive analyses in ihese two works. My 
dialogue will be primarily with Dcriida and his worlvS^ and with Professor 
Caputo in his two works as interpreter and defender of Derrida. 

The spectre of Derrida has Ijccn haunting the western intellectual 
world for some three decades now. His iTicssagc has been getting across. 
Totalities tend to totalize and oppress. Identities tend to exclude 
and marginalize, Dogmas dogmatize, and systems produce closure- 
Messianic claims spill blood. Fundamentalist claims to certainty and 
definitivcness create hell on earth. Hence the need to subvert total [ties, 
disrupt the same^ complicate simplicities^ problematizc the complacent 
contaminaLe the pure, and destabilize alt systems and fundamentalisms, 
by exposing them to the shock of alterltyj the demand of the other^ the 
trauma of the uiiexpected. 1'hat ts^ to deconstruct. Deconslruction is 
'the delimitation of totalization in aM its forms^^ the thought of 'an 
absolute heterogeneity that unsettles all the assurances of the same 
witliin which we comfortably ensconce ourselves'.^ 

In the area of [eii^icn Derrida's deconstiuctlon has been most chal- 
lenging in his treatments of negative dieologv^ and the messianic, Ehe 
first showing what God should not be, the second what (jod should be 
without being. 



167 



168 Phih.'iGplTy ofRi'lightu m the 21it Century 

Derrlda's deconstruction of nej^ative theology 

Deirida discerns two different voices in iiegaEive theology. The first 

voice is hypcrousiology. Even though negative theology denies the 
possibility of attiibuting names to God and places God beyond all 
iiames, it docs not stop at negation but affirms God precisely in God's 
hypcresscntial reality. It is a higher^ more refined niodalizalion of 
ontotheology, a variation en the metapliysics of presence.'* For all Its 
negations, it claims deep down Lo 'know' what God is. The God of 
negative thcologj"^ in facl^ turns out to be 'a transcendental signified^ 
die dream of being without diffenuKi^, of bein^ outside the text, outside 
the general tcxtj outside the play of traces'/^ Negative theolog>^ feels as 
secure in its possession of an object as positive theology; it is a triumph 
of presence over representation.^ 

There is^ however, another voice in ne;^ative theology. As an inuption 
from the depth, it expresses a yearnings a movement^ a passion for the 
wholly other of which we all dream and by whicli wc iccl addressed, a 
deeply affirmative desire for 'something always essentially other than 
the prevailing regime of presence^ something tout autie'7 It embodies a 
passion for the impossible, a movement of transgression over and 
beyond the present, a response to a primordial promise. It embodies 
the spirit of relentless critical negation tn pursuit of an ultimate that 
always remains wholly other^ a kind of a generalized apophatics^ a 
Tcenosis of discourse'.** Everything must pass through 'the aporias of 
negative theolog\^'', and only a discourse 'contaminated^ by negative 
theology can be trusted.^ 

What does deconstruction do for negative theology? Deconstruction 
does not provide a secuic foundation or a horizon for the intelligibility 
of tlie content of negative theology- Instead, by reinscribing or resituat- 
Ing negative theology within tlie general movement of the trace^ dif- 
fera}fc^, and undccidability, within all the multiplicities and ambiguities 
of language and history, the basic situation of all human exfKrienee 
according to Derrida, deconstruction preserves faith as faith, as some- 
thing 'blind^ without the privilege of savoir, avoir, nthi voir^ both accen- 
tuating the passion of faith as faith struggles to take a leap and decide 
for the impossible in the midst of the very undecidability that consti- 
tutes its vcrj' structure^ and maintaining faith as an indeterminate, 
open-ended groping and hope in the wholly other Difference precludes 
the possibility of knowledge, vision, or face-to-face tuilon with God, as 
it always recontextualizcs faith, exposing it to indefinite substitutions, 
translations, aiid interpretations. Ontothcology takes faith as a mode 



^?j_«J^?j Kyo^i:s;^uk Miu 169 

of presence outside the movement of diffemnce and the play of traces and 
turns it into something secure^ positive and closed^ geiiciaLmg the pcrnU 
etous dangers of absolutism and triumph alism inherent in all fundamen- 
talisms and all 'doternii liable' faiths. "'Closure spells trouble, ...closure 
spells exclusion, cxclusiveness; closure spills blood, doctrinal, confcs- 
stnnsi, theological, poliMcatj LnslUutional bloody and eventuially^ it 
never fails, real blood/*"^ 

Rtliijion as messianic lit>pe 

For Derrida, religion is a response to the call and demand of the wholly 
other, an invocation or prayer ('comcD for its advent, and the mes- 
sianic praxis of justice here and now corresponding to that invocation 
and demand. 

The 'object' or 'God' of this religion remains the Vholly olher^ 
resisting all reduction lo a humaii concept, category or horizon. It lies 
beyond all human imagination, credibility, graspability or deter- 
minability, beyond all human logos, tclcologicajj, eschatological and 
otherwise. In contrast to the God of ontotheolog}^ who remains Infi- 
nlteiy and eternally the Same'^^ and in fact ^thc name of indifference 
itsetr,*^ the God of de construction is: 

the name of the impossible, of novelty, of the coming of the Other, 
of the tout rtiibi, of what is coming with the shock of an absolute 
surprise, wiih the trauma of absolute hclero^cneiry\ Gast in a decon- 
structivc slant, God is not the p-ossibJe but the imjx>ssiblCj not the 

eternal but the futural.-^'^ 

There is no transcendental horizon within which God can be awaited, 

expcctedp or made knowable; God shatters all human horizons. 

Dcrrida is especially insistent that the wholly other is beyond all 
determination or determinacy. A determinable future, with a deter- 
minable telos, is a future that can be anticipated within the horizon of 
a particular aim, of what Is possible, and thus a future as present- Pres- 
ence, possibility, determinacy: these arc, for Dcrrida, one and the same- 
The fumre of the wholly other Ls an 'absolute" future, a future absolved 
from the regime and horizon of presence and identity, from whatever 
is presentable, programmable, imaginable, foreseeable, beyond the tra- 
ditional dualisms of essence and existence, universal and particular, 
Ideal and real. The wholly other is 'structurally' and therefore ""aiways' 
to come. It is precisely the function of the wholly other to shatter and 



170 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

shock the horizon of the same and forcscciiblc and open up the 
promise and possibility of something wholly other The wholly other is 
Identifiable with neiiliet a determinable faith nor a determinable 
messiah nor a determinable end of hisLory nor a determinable degree 
of justice. It is also to be distinguished from any Utopian or Kantian 
re^lative ideal, which foo has its own determinate conlent. The 
whoHy other is stiiiply (he beyond^ the aU'delA. It is impossible to 
measure the extent lo which the wholly other is being approximated 
or realized in a society. ^^ 

Reli^ioji addresses its prayer, its 'comeJ' to this wholly otiier in 
response to the latter's solicitation and demand. 

To call upon God, to call God^s name^ to pray and w^eep and have a 
passioii for God Is to call for the tout autie, for something that 
breaks up the hohum homogeneity of the same and all but knocks 
us dead. The name of God is a name that calls for the other, that 
calls from the other, the name that the other calls, that calls upon 
us like Elijah at the doofj and that calls for things ncw^^^ 

The invocation is a primordial affirmation based on faith and hope that 
the impossible will be possible, the impossibility of a saving breach in 
the chain of presence and totality, of a liberating breakthrough in the 
oppressive horizon of the same, of the messianic emergence of the 
novum beyond al] human expectations and calculations. 

Outside all human mastery and control vlea.^ hofpes for a break 
within the interstices of the laws of regularity^ an outbreak of 
chance within the crevices of tiie continuous flow of presence. 

It 'siiently teai's open lived time and ordinary language/ 'renders them 
always already structurally open to what is coming^ and 'prohibits 
{piu!} closure while soliciting transcendence {Se p:i^)\^^ ii is 'the order^ 
or disorder^ of messianic tinie^ of v^nir and m^e^iir, that disturbs the 
order of presence'.'^ This messianic Invocation of the wholly other 
Embodies ^a certain structural wakefulness or openness to an impossi- 
ble breach of the present, shattering the conditions of possibility, by 
which we are presently circumscribed'.'^ 

For Derridaj tout imtrc est tviit aattv. The wholly other is every other. 
The wholly other is not only God but also every human bein^. As Lcv- 
inas saySn TnfiniLe alterily^ or 'absolute singularity^ belongs to both God 
and human beings. For Derrida, this invalidates both the Kierkegaardian 



^?j_«J^?j Kyo^i:s;^uk Min 171 

distinction between the ethical (the finite relationship to the finite) 
and the religious [the infinite relationship lo the infinite) and the 
Lcvlnasian distinction between ethics and religion. ^^ Religion U not 
separable from ethics nor, for that inattcrp from political and legal 
matters. Wherc^^er infinite alterity is at issue, there is religion. This is 
why the hope in tlie wholly other is also a nicssianic hope for a 'uni- 
versal culture of singularities'^ in which justice will be done to the 
other in its itreducibic singularity- 
Messianic time internjpts the living present with the demand for 
justice. Messianic lime is prophetic Lime, ihe time of justice which is 
always to come yet issues a call for justice here and now. Justice 
deferred is justice denied. Deconstruction 1s not meant to be a soft 
sighing for the future, but a way of deciding now and being impas- 
sioned In the mcmcnl^^^ Dijferaiice: 

docs not mean only deferral^ delay, and procrastination, but the 
spacing out, the extension between memory and promise or a-ienir, 
which opens up the hcre-now In all of its urgency and absolute 
singularity, in the imminence of the instant. The call of what is 
coming calls for action now.^^ 

Justice docs not tolerate present injustice in the name of a gradual 

approximation of an ideal but demands justice here and now. It is 
by definilion 'impatient, uncompromising, and unconditional. No dif- 

ferance without alterity, no alterity ivlthout stngu[arity^ no singularity 
without here-now/^^ 

The freedom of the wholly other from all determinate contents makes 
Derrtda's religion ""a messlanism without religion. ...even a messianic 
without mcssianism\^"* a faith without dogma, a religiozi without reli- 
gion. It is a commitment to the wholly other In all its nominaUst free- 
dom and absolute heterogeneity without an equal commitment to the 
determinate content of a particular rclij;;ion, dogma, institution or 
programme. Such a commitment to determinacy, for Derrlda, entails 
totalitarian reduction of the other to the same and generates violence 
and Tvar^^ The 'call for a fixed and identifiable other, foreseeable and 
foregraspable.-. would release the manic aggression of a program^ the 
mania of an all-out rush for a future-present.^^* Thias, deconstruction 
'liccps a safe distance from ever letting its faith be a faith in a determi- 
nate thing or person, from ever contracting the tout autre within the 
horizons of the same^^^ The invocation for the coming of the other is 
an apocalyptic prayer for the advent of messianic time, but it is an 



172 Pfiih.'inphy ofRi'fii^ou m tta^ 21%i Century 

apocalypse without (determinate) visioRj truEh, or revelation, an apoc- 
alypse without apocaly'pse. 

This description of Derridean rcli^iosi should also make clear the 
minimal character of its content. The heart of that religion lies in its 
mcsslanicit>' or its prophetic passion for justice, 'the infriitle respect of 
the singularity itnd iiiflnLte alterlty of the other'r^ This is where religion 
and deconstructlon conYcrgc- It Is the very nature ot messianiclty; 
howe\^er, to shatter all determinate horizons with their delerminate 
contents and llius to exclude all detcrminatCj particular^ historical 
religions and messianisrns. Dcrnda's messianic hope and promise 
always remain ''absolutely undetermined'' and 'eschatologlcal'.-^ To 
endorse a determinate 3'c3iglon is to spell closure and to spill blood- It Is 
important to purify the messianic of all determinate contents by epttche 
and abstraction so as to intensify its urgency, but this also amounts to 
''desertification* or rendering of religion into a diy and barren desert, 
deprived of its specific comforts and intelligLbllities and reduced lo a 
universal, formal structure with a minimal content, 'the messianic in 
general, as a thinking of the other and of the event to comeV^^^ 'the 
opening to the future or to the coming of the other as the advent of 
justice^ bLLt without horizon of expectation and without prophetic 
prefiguration',"*^ a primordial Idea of justice and democracy to come - 
to be distinguished from any of their current coiiceptions - as the 
Irreducible and undeconstructlbic ultimate- Religion is reduced to the 
bare minimum of an atheologtcal, open-ended, negative^ or apophattc 
process of justice, a movement toward a New International as 'a 
community without communitj^^^ or 'the friendship of an alliance 
without tnstitution^^^ Particular religions are nourished by their 
''place\ theit history, tradition, nation, language and people, and gener- 
ate the ^politics of place and the wars over placed ^^ Derrida seeks to 
liberate the messianic of universal justice from such politics and wars 
by turning it into a desert, 'a kind of placelcss, displaciit;^ place - or 
a place for the displaced', ^^ a postgeographical, universal religion, a 
'religion for all and evcrvTvhere','^^ a Derridean equivalent of the Kantian 
'rellgioti within the limits of reason alone", although reason is never 
without faith. 



Living together with those wiio are different, especially with respect for 
their difference^ has always been a central problem of human history. 
Individually and collectively our instinct has hccn to subjugate them 



to our system of identity that makes no room for their difference, and 
to reduce and violate them in their iiiLegrity as the other. This occurs at 
all levels of human existence, individual and social^ in aJI spheres of 
society^ economics, politics and culture^ and with consequences in all 
areas of philosophy, ontolog}^, epistcmolog^^, ethics^ aesthetics and 
philosophy of religion_ What Emmanuel Lcvinas calls the 'horror of 
the othcr"-^" and its correlative^ the tenor of the same have been as 
pervasive, as destructive, and as compelling as any original sin in 
liuman history. The t^-\'o global wars of the present century, the many 
regional and local conflicts from the Korean War to Bosnia, the count- 
less racist^ ethnic and religious strifes from the Jewish holocaust to 
South African apartheid and racism in the United States to the bloody 
struggles between Jews and Arahs in Palestine^ asid the growing recog- 
nition of the sexist violation of women throughout human history: all 
of these have deepened our awareness, and intensified the urgency in 
dealing with the problem of the other in our century. On the eve of the 
twenty-first century most societies also increasingly face the problem 
of living together under conditions of religious and cultural plurality. 
Global capitalism has been bringing together different cultures 
and making them interdependentj relativizing all cultural absolutes^ 
compelling all to become aware of the problem of the other, and 
imposing the political hnpcrativc of dialogue- 
Given these historical urgencies, it is no exaggeration to say that 
today we cannot live without a heav^ dose of what deconstruct ion 
stands for^ its critique of the terror of tlie same in all its forms^ and its 
vision of justice and democracy. All modern philosophies have been 
critical of the given, from f>cscartes through Kant, Hegel and Marx 
to pragmatism and critical theory. Deconstruction has few peers, how- 
ever^ in the single-mi ndedness of its attention to the problem of the 
other, in its universalization of thai problem, and in the radicaiity vs^ith 
which it subverts all traditional ideologies from Plato to Heidegger. To 
enter the world of deconstruction is to enter a world without absolute 
principles, horizons, foundations^ and centres from which to judge the 
other^ to relnscribe or rcsltuate all our t>eliefs within the general move- 
ment of difference that renders all identities heterogeneous and defers 
all presences to the play of traces, and to live accordingly^ without nos- 
talgia for absolute certainties but also with respect for difference and 
always with hope - in the case of messianic postmodernism - in the 
coming of the absolutely other. Nothing can boast of pure idcntltyn 
nothing can insist on pure presence, all reality is marked by differenti- 
ation and deferral. In an age that has suffered so rauch from the terror 



174 PfjihsGphy ofRi'lii^mr m tin: 21%i Century 

of ihe same, a! a time when a pluralist scnsibtlit)^ is de n^uair for 
survival and peace on earth, in a world where the 'sacrifice of Isaac 
continues every day\^^ dcconstruction should remain, even for those 
of us who do not accepc it, a thorn in our side, a perjx^tua! reminder of 
the dangers into which monocentrism can plunge the world, keeping 
us in a state of 'vigilant Insomnia' (Levinas)-^^ for the cry of the other_ 

In this spirit, much of Dcrrtda's philosophy of religion dcscr^'cs and 
demands attentive and respectftjl meditation. His de cons l rue I ion of 
negative theolo^^ and determinate rclij^tons, his description of the 
messianic as the wholly other, his refusal to separate reli^ioii and poli- 
tics, messianicity and justice: thc:>c are important antidotes against 
the terror of the same luaking In religion, in its claim to closure, its 
dogmatism, its fundamentalism, its totalitarianism. Left to themseh'eSf 
religions, including believing philosophers and theologians, delude 
themselves into thinking that they 'knoTV^ wiio God is, with only 
lip service to the classical thesis of the 'incomprehensibility' of 
God. Augustine's question, which 15 also Derrida's, remains and should 
remain conipclling in its very challenger What exactly Is tl lliat I love 
when I love my God? In this regard, Caputo is quite right in locating 
the specific contribution of dcconslruclion in providing for the reli- 
gious believer 'a saving apophatics, a certain salutary:' purgation of the 
posittviLy of belief^ wliich reminds us all that we do not know what 
Is coming, what is tout autre' ^^^ A periodic ' contamination ■" of religion 
with negative theology should he a wholesome exercise that would 
also challenge each religion to transcend its determinacy and prohc 
its own messianic depth for the impossible possibility of the wholly 
other. 

What can we say about Dcrftda's 'religion without religion'? Derrida's 
religion is deliberately minimal in its content, It consists in an existen- 
tial commitment to the impossible possibility of the absolutely other, 
in a prayerful invocation for the advent of the wholly other beyond all 
human reason, calculation and imagination, and in the praxis of jus- 
tice in response to the call and demand of that other. It Is a deliberate, 
extreme abstraction from the content of all determinate atid deter- 
minable religions, their dogmas, rituals and institutions, and therefore 
also an intellectual and emotional desert wilhout ilie nourishing com- 
forts of tradition and communit^^ It places itself beyond the distinc- 
tions of theism and atheism, religion and seeularisnij as different 
therefore from the atheism of Enlightenment rationalism as it is from 
traditional religious faith. One could say that it is the 'logical' expres- 
sion of the faith of the modern Western intellectual who has been 



^?j_«J^?j Kyo^i:s;^uk Min 175 

thoroughly alienated from all institutional rcli^ons as well as from all 
traditional ralionalitics yd who cannot stmpiy surrender themselves to 
sheer, destructive nihilism and irresponsible rclati^^snl- Even in thor- 
ough alienation and utter blindness one still hopes and gropes, beyond 
all reason and faith, for tlic possibility of the impossible, for something 
ultimate and undcconstructible, tlie advent of messianic justice, with- 
out quite knowing what to call it. II is 'a search without hope for 
hope', in a space where the prophets arc not far away'.^^ Derrida's reli- 
gion is perhaps the last refuge of the Western intellectual elite commit- 
ted to l>olh the protest of modern atheism and the Blochian spirit of 
Utopian hope. 

I do not say this in disparagement The cultural situation Derrida 
depicts is not hctiona!. It is a situation that has been facing Western intel- 
lectuals for some time and that is now increasingly facing intellectuals in 
the rest of the world as wcIL It is no wonder that Christian theology has 
likewise beeii trying to cope precisely with that situation in some of its 
representatives such as Paul Tillich and Karl Rahncr It is quite relevant 
here to mention Tillich "s dcconstruclion of traditional faith into 
'absolute faith', which is not faith in a determinate object but a state of 
being grasped by the power of bcing-itsclfp which in turn is neither 
personal nor pantheistic but goes beyond both, wliich can only be 
called ^the God above Go-d'.^^ Rahner^s increasiiigly iiegativc reference 
to God as 'al^solute', 'incomprehensible mystery' and 'absolute future' 
is likewise an attempt to make Cliristianity credible hi the present 
intellectual climate^ as is his minimalisi, existential dcfmiilon of the 
Christian content as the commitment that Ve are inetuctably engaged 
by the incomprehensible mystery whom we call God^ and who cease- 
lessly and silently grasps us and ehallenges our hope and love even 
when we show little concern for him in the practice of our lives or 
even actually deny him in theory' .^"^ 

This is alsOj however^ precisely where the issue lies. Neither Tillich 
nor Rahncr goes on to propose, as docs Derrida, an extreme al:kstraction 
from the concrete content of determinate Christian faith. They may try 
to criticize and sublate the determinate historical content ol" Christian 
faith into something more credible and relevant through existential or 
transcendental herniencutic; it is not their intention to do away vslth 
the essential mediation of faith bv determinate historical contents and 
produce a rcSij^ion without religion^ which Dcrrida does. Granted that 
we cannot live without deconstnjctloii today, as I believe we cannot, 
granted that we have to reinscribe relation and politics within the 
general movement of diffi'nvjce, can we live on deconstructlon alone? 



176 Pfiihsnphy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

1 do not think wc can. The very strcn^h of dc construction, the radical- 
ity ofits negations, may also be its very weakness. 

Let me begin with Derrida's depreciation of determinate religion. 
Derrtda has nothing l>uL aversion for concrete, detcmiinale religions 
with their historical content. They are simply identified witli reiflca- 
tion and closure and as so many sources of nl>solutism, Iriumphaltsm 
and bloody coiiOicts. It is not that some determinate religions are 
triuniphalislic or thaL all determinate religions ^omctifiia; generate 
triumph alism and absolutism; it is rather that the very idea of determi- 
nation or dctermttiability entails presence, identity, and the imperial- 
ism of the same. Even though Dcrrida himself derives his concept of 
the messianic from existing, determinate Jewish and Christian escha- 
tologics by bending and repeating them 'with a difference^ and even 
though Caputo himself admits that Derrida's own messianic religion 
has all the marks of a determinate religion and can survive only wltli 
the support of determinate, instituttonalizcd messianic eschatologies/^ 
still, determinate religions remain only 'consummately dangcrous',^^ 
with no positive virtues to show. As a non-cssentialist, Derrida may not 
say, but he docs imply, pace Caputo^ that 'theology or religion always 
and essentially means bad ncws^ the 6U}<:ien re^ime^ a reactionary, world- 
negattng, and fear-driven pathology'.*^ 

This means t^vo things. On the one hand^ the wholly other of mcsslan^ 
Icity cannot and should not become actual and concrete through incarna- 
tion in a determinate loJighJti. The only relation bctu^een messianicity 
and determinate messianic religions is one of relentless negation, period. 
The messianic is not what a determiciale religion is. The messianic is 
nowhere embodied because it is not in principle embodiable- It is not 
only that the messianic always transcends any of its concretizing histori- 
cal mediations but also that it should not be so mediated because such 
mediation necessarily involves a fall, a corruption. 

On the other hand, it also means that determinate historical religions 
have no positive mediaLing function to provide precisely in tlie service 
of the messianic, the wiiolly other in terms of nourishing faith and 
praxis. As modes of frozen presence and idenlityn determinate religions 
have no principle of self-transcendence, self-criticism, and self-reform 
within themselves; there are no resources of a dialectic between the 
present and the future, the determinate and the determining in histor- 
ical religions. Between the wholly other aiid historical religions there is 
no mediation, only radical otherness. 

Derrida's own religion without religion, therefore^ can remain pure 
and holy only because it is nowhere embodied or institutionalized in a 



^?j_«J^?j Kyo^i:s;^uk Min 177 

dctcrmlnaEc religion. It en^a^es in the dcconstmction of all dcterml- 
iialc religions from the transcendent heigliL of purc^ disembodied^ 
angelic ideality, jjust as Enllf;htenment rationalism has l>cen engaging 
Ln the eritieal dismissal of all religions from the self-legitimating height 
of piarc, uninstttutionalizedn ahistorieal reason. Instead of advising con- 
crete religions^ therefore^ on how to bear bcller witness to the wholly 
other under the conditions of history and necessary institutionaliza- 
tJonn it simply says no! indiscriminately to all determinate religions 
regardless of their differences in the degree and kind of witnessing they 
do. It is a yes! to the messianic hut a noJ to all historical attempts to 
embody it. Derrida's messianic reservation, like the Christian cschato- 
logical prov'iso, ts more interested in condemning religions for what in 
any event they cannot do, that is^ achieve a perfect realization of the 
messianic on earth, ihaii iii empowering them to do what they can, 
that is, bear a more effective ivitness to the messianic even if no 
wLtnesstng will ever measure up to the full demand of ihe messianic. 
Derrida's rehgion without rcIig"ion remains an ahistorieal abstraction. 

The messianic wholly other impinges on our history, therefore, only in 
the mode of interruption, disruptionn discontinuity, surprise and opposi- 
tion^ and only in the experience of the impossible, unimaginable^ unfore- 
seeable and unproRrammable. What we can do by our own power and 
with our own foresight and planning and wliat we experience within the 
realm of the possible and the foreseeable, within what Derrlda callSj with 
sweeping generality^ tlie horizon of the same: these have no messianic or 
religious significance. That is to say, our moral and political actions in 
history have no religious weight because we undertake most of them 
with our own responsihilityf with our own knowledge of what is possible 
and what is noi^ and with our own freedom to risk the unknown but 
always with caution and prudence. The ancient dualism of body and soul 
returns in the guise of a new opposition of what is determinate and 
what is indeterminate, what is possible and what is Impossible^ what is 
foreseeable and what is unforeseeable- We encounter the God of decon- 
struction only as a matter of 'absolute surprised 

What Derrlda says about dclermiiiaLc religions also applies to deter- 
minate pohtical praxis. The messianic as such - the ^universal culture 
of singularities'- or justice and democracy are 'structurally" and there- 
fore ^always' to come, and should not be identified with a determinate 
present form of law or political structure. Although the perfection of the 
messianic lies in the 'absolute' future^ not in a fiiture that can l>ccome 
present^ its demand is for justice ^hcrc and now'. The messianic 
provides the light in wliich all present forms of justice and democracy 



178 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%t Century 

however pcrfccEj wilt be judged and challenged lo transcend ihem- 
sclves- Messianic politics lies in the hope for ^an lEiipossiblc breach of 
die present, shaciering die conditions of possibility^ by which we are 
presently CKCumscribcd\'*^ 

The messianic rhetoric of 'shatterin^j 'new'H ^unforeseeabk^ and so 
on creates the impression of a 'radical' politics as appropriate praxis for 
die messianic hope that deconstniction constantly evokes. When it 
comes to political praxis, however, it is anylhin^ but radical. Dccon- 
structive politics involves operating withu} the conventions and rules 
of the prevailing order - there is no other place to operate - "'tKnding"' 
and 'repeating' them 'widi a difference^ and 'twisting free of the samQj 
altering It just enough to let a little alterlt)^ loose', which is different 
from ^straightforward opposition, confrontational countering, which 
succumbs to dialectical assimilation'-'^* Furthermore, we 'can only 
prepare for the incoming of the other^ but we cannot invent it, cannot 
effect it, bring it about, by a cunning deconstructive agency. Wc arc 
called upon, paradoxically, to prepare for the incalculable, to prepare 
without calculating In advance^ The 'only' concern of dcconstructlon 
is the time to come: 'allowing the adventure or the event of the tout 
autre to conic \^^ 

Deconstructive poHtical praxis, then, conies down to 'hoping' for an 
impossible breach of the present, 'bending' and 'twisLing free' of the 
present rules and conventions to let a little aiterity loose', and thus 
'preparing^ for the coming of justice, which we cannot 'calculate' or 
'program' or 'contror. It is opposed to 'confrontational countering' 
because it would ^succumb to dialectical assimilaLion^ At best, we have 
a 'politics of exodus, of the emigre^ 'a subversion of fixed assumptions 
and a privileging of disorder', or 'responsible anarchy'-^'-Must as dccon- 
structlon reduces rchgion to a minimal content, so it reduces politics to 
the passive minimum of hoping, bending a [illle, and waiting- There is 
no substantive, systematic reflection on the djiiamics and trends of 
contemporary history, on the possibilities they contain for liberation 
and oppression^ on prospects for political mobilization for the libera- 
tion of the oppressed and marginalized others that dcconsiiuction 
seems so much to care for, nor on political "structures that mediate 
between the messianic ideal always to come and present political 
praxis that will concretize for a societj^ and for a time at least the 
demand of the messianic. 

This is not accidental. Politics in the classical sense presupposes that 
human beings can, collectively^ as a community, acquire the knowl- 
edge of their historical situation and mobilize themselves to produce a 



Au.'u:!^^} Ky^yyi^-iuk Men 179 

political structure that will bost embody thctr fprevallm^) ideals of 
justice in that situation according to their knowledge. This is predicated 
on faith and hope In the possibility of collective human action and col- 
lective human wisdom. This faith and hope have soanelimes been viiidi- 
cated by history, as witness the gradual, often, uphill, but^ by htstortcal 
standards, truly significant achievements in democratic institutions, as 
they have also sometiines been contradicted by iiistory, as witness the 
many violations of human rights and the often incalculal>le suffering 
brought about by totalitarian regimes. Wc do not, however, hare much 
choice here. It lakes precisely collective actioii and collective wisdom to 
combat the terror of totalitarian oppression^ as history has also amply 
demonstrated; the only alternative to the oppression by a totalitarian 
regime is to set up a democratic regime. In any event, classical politics 
presupposes tliis faiih and ho|x^ In collective action and collective 
wisdom. 

It is precisely this faith that Dcrrida lacks, as is evident in his 'histor- 
ical and politicar investigation into the seciret of responsibility in The 
Gift of D^iitti.^^ Dcrrida defines duty or responsibilily as a relation 
between a person in his or her 'absolute singularity^ and the other in 
his or her equally 'absolute singularity'/^ This cthicai relationship^ 
however, immediately exposes me to the risk of absolute sacrifice 
because J cannot at ihc same time respond to the call of all the other 
others, an infinite numlx^r of them, vs^ho are also addressing an 
absolute appeal to me in their respective infinite singularities . This is 
the paradox, scandal and aporia of the concept of responsibility, which 
reveals the concept at Its limit and fmitude. 

'As soon as I enter into a reiatioai wiLh the other, with the gaze, [ook, 
request, lo\'e, command, or call of the other, I kncrw^ that 1 can respond 
only by sacrificing ethics, that is, by sacrificing whatever obliges me to 
also respond, in the same way, in the same instaitt, to all the others. 
I offer a gift of death, I betray, 1 don't need to raise my knile over my 
son on Mount \loriah for that. Day and night, at every instant, on all 
t]ie Mount Moriahs of this worlds I am doing that, raising my knife 
over what I love and must love, over those to whom I owe absolute 
fidelity, Incommensurably. Abraham is faithful to God only in his 
absolute treachery, in the betrayal of his own and of the uniqueness of 
each one of thcm^ exemplified here in his only beloved son/^^ 

Fulfilling an obligation to an other entails sacrificing and betraying 
all other obligations to all the other others including those dying of 



180 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

stan'atlon and sickness. Everyone is being sacriTiccd to c^^cr)^one else in 
'this land of Moriah Lliat is our hahilat cvury second of everyday'.^"* The 
aporia of responsibility is thai there Is no Justification for sacrificing 
all ihcse others^ the 'ethical or political gencralitj^.^^ Dcrrida asks^ 
'How would you e^'cr justif):^ the fact that you sacrifice all the cats in 
the world to the cat that you feed at home every morniii;^ for years, 
whereas other cats die of hunger at every instant? Not Lo mention 
other people?'^^ in this sense, then, the sacrifice of Isaac, a beloved 
son, the infinite other to whom 1 owe an absolute duty, is ^inscribed in 
tlie structure of our cxistcncc'--^^ Likewise, behind the appearances of 
normality' and legitimacy, of moral discourse and good conscience^ 
society organizes and participates in the death and sickness of millions 
of children through tlic very structure of its market, mechanisms of its 
external debt, and other inequities. We allow the sacrifice of others in 
order to avoid being sacrificed ourselves. ^^ 

VVhatn then, can one do about this ethical scandal? That Derrida pro- 
vides no answer is pt^rhaps indicative of the limits of his horizon_ One 
can say that he provides no answer because 'this land of Moriah' is \iur 
verj^ habitat', because such a scandal is '[nscrihcd in the structure 
of our existence^ about which, therefore, we cannot do anything. 
His interest is lii accentuating the aporia of moral experience and com- 
plicating our moral simplicities, within the structural limits of our exis- 
tence. Is such a sandal, however^ really 'inscribed in the structure of 
our existence ? Or, does U pointy rather^ to the limits of Dcrrida's own 
-deconstructlonist horizon? 

Deirlda's horizon, as that of his two mentors, Kierkegaard and 
Levinas, is that of tlie individual in her 'absolute' and 'infinite' 'singu- 
larity'. As a moral agent each of us is 'infinitely other in Its absolute 
singularity, inaccessible^ solitaryn transcendent, nonmanifest, originar- 
ily nonpiesent to my ego\^^ From this perspective of the isolated 
individual, Derrida goes on to ask^ What can 7 do^ precisely in my 
abjioiiste siti^tiiwity und isoSatioii, to avoid the suiiering of millions of 
starving children and millions of cats other than mine^ since I cannot 
respond 'hi the same way, in the same Instaiit, lo all the others?^"^ The 
answ^er, of course, has to be 'not much . An individual as such cannot 
respond to all these moral appeals in the same way at the same time^ 
nor does she have the resources to respond to many of them with any 
adequacy even if she has the time to respond. The assumption, how- 
ever, is false. 

Modern history amply demonstrates that In situations where w^hat is 
at stake is the ivelfare of a large number of people serious enough to 



constitute the 'public' interest or common good, the appropriate a^ent 
is nol the isolated individual but ihe political communily as such. 
Whenever our serious welfare is at stake and we cannot attend to that 
Avelfare as isolated individuals, wc do so as united individuals^ togethern 
tliat iSn as a community. We cannot protect our security individually^ 
so UT do so as a communily by insliluting the police and the military 
as organs of the state. Wc cannot provid(^ education for ouj^clvcs indi- 
vidually, so we do so as a community t>y establishing public education. 
We cannot guarantee minimum welfare for ourselves individually, 
so wc do so as a eommunit)^ by making sure that Ihe economy is ade- 
quately fui:ictioning through monetary, fiscal and other policies, by 
establishing minimum wage laws, and by instituting social security 
for old age and times of sickness. This common or collective care 
for the common good is precisely what Is meant by politics in the 
classical sense. What we cannot do iiidividually we do together, that 
iSj politically^* 

If wc change the horizon from that of the isolated individual to that 
of the polilical community, from the lone 'I lo the 'wc'^ and ask not^ 
'What can J do as iin imiividu^if?' but rather 'What can we do to^etherT 
the moral aporia that Derrida weeps over need not be as great or as 
scandalous as he makes it out to be. Wc together, that is, various coun- 
tries and private associations including the United NaUons^ have been 
alleviating the suffering o( millions of starving and sick children. 1 as 
an individual do my part by paying my fair share of taxes and making 
my fair share of contributions, which will both hire aitd enable other 
Individuals, that Ls, relief workers and government agents, to provide 
the relief. If 30 many cats other than mine arc sufferinj; as to constitute 
their relief a matter of the public interest, we can, through the govern- 
ment^ organize such relief by setting up shehcrs for cats, as many com- 
munities arc already doing. The fact that our existing political means 
are not adequate to match outstanding needs is no argument against 
the poliLical solution; it is an argument for improving it. 

This 'politicar approach does not eliminate the moral aporia that so 
concerns Dcrrida. In some sensCj given the existential limitations of 

"1 '1 '1 "' - - r b'i^ 

the moral and material resources of humanity, sucli a moral aporia will 
indeed alwa^'s remain. Such an aporia, howevcFn can be exaggerated 
when it i5 approached only from the individual perspective, and 
become ideologically pernicious when it Ls used as an argumcitt for 
political fatalism and neglect of available political means. It is critical 
to remember how much humanity has achicv'cd by working to^etherH 
collectively, that is, politically: elimination of hunger, illiteracy and 



182 Pfiih.'iophy of Ri'lii^f^ir m tta^ 21%i Century 

many forms of epidemic in many parts of the world is, by historical 
standards^ an achievement too j^real and too noble to be merely humil- 
iated by a misplaced messianic or escliatological proviso, alchougli it 
Ls not great enough and often too ideologically tainted to serve moral 
complacency among us. 

However, it is precisely this 'politicar horizon with its faith and hope 
ill ihe possibility of collective action and collective wisdom that 
DeiTida lacks. Derrida's emphasis on the Infinite singularity' of the indi-- 
vidual and his deconstruetionist distrust of totaUtyj community^ and 
unity for fear of 'fusion"^^ do not provide confidence in the possibility 
of 'collective' action: such an action is either too ridden with otherness 
and division to be genuinely collective or too totalitarian to respect the 
infinite alterity of the agents, ^-^ Derrida Is more interested in unmasli- 
ing hidden oppressions in a totality than in encouraging wholesome 
collective action_ lii^cwlse, his emphasis on the absolute transcendence 
of the messianic and its radical discontinuity with any dcternlinal:^lc 
political structure or institution or law does not encourage mobiliza- 
tion of collective wisdom in the interest of a determinate reform or rev- 
olution as a historically appropriate institutionalization of messianic 
justice. Instead, Derrida is more interested in condemning current 
Institutions for jwt being a perfect model of justice than in providing a 
vision of hctter institutioiis that they am become or judicious reflec- 
tions on the how of the justice that must Indeed be done here and 
now. As inftnite asvrametrv of the relalion to the other'- as 'incalcula- 
bility of the gift and singularity of the an-economic ex-position to 
others',^"* justice lies in principle ''beyond' all right, calculation, com- 
merce, beyond ^juridicat-moral rules^ norms, or representations^ within 
an Inevitable totalizing horizon'.**^ In this sense, it is difficult to dis- 
agree with Richard Dernstcin when he accuses Derrtda's idea of a 
'democracy to come' of hcin^ 'an impotent, vague abstraction', or with 
Thomas McCarthy when he accuses Derrida of bein^ more interested 
in destabilizing universalist structures than In reconstructing protective 
institutions for rights and dignity.^* 

VVilliam James once spoke of two attitudes towards Inith and error- 
One attiEudc is that of the sceptic, who ts driven by an obsessive fear of 
falling into error and docs not want to beltcve in anything except on 
sufficient evidence. The other is the attitude of the pragmatist, svho is 
more driven by the hope of finding truth thati hy the fear of falling 
into error and is therefore willing to risk even believing in error in 
order to find truth-^^ Deconstruction is more like the sceptic than the 
pragmatist. it is fundamentally fearful of all determinate embodiments 



of human sociality in history because of the terror of the same. It may 
offer prayers and tears for the coming of the wholly other and its mes 
sianic lustlcCr but it does not want to dirty its liands by working at 
«stahlislijng determinate institutions of rcHgion and politics. In the 
name of diffemuce it flees from the liistorical dcterminacy of matter, 
body, senses, objectivity and sociality, the world of presence, identity 
and totality^ and takes refuge in the dream of the impossil^lc. Perhaps 
deconst ruction should inscribe itself In the quite possible dialectic 
of the determinable within history so as to keep its difference human, 
not angehc. Please remember: in human history all negations arc 
determhmte negations.^ 



Notti 

1^ j-Bhn L>- C^puto (ed_)j Decoustnictio}^ Ui 4? NuisfK^Si: tj Convers^ition witfi j^icqites 
Deiritia (Ne\s York^ Foidham University Press^ I???), and John D. Caputo^ 
The Prijy^5 ami Teur^ tifjncqites. Denhiu:^ Rdigk\}? withoiit Reiigim} ^Blooming- 
ton: Indiana University PresSj 19975. 

Z. Frayt^fs, 126. 

4^ Jacques E>erradar Mar;fi}i5 of PhUo^opf^'', trans. A3an Bass (Chicago: The 
LTniver^aty oi Chicago Pfes^, 19S2p^ 6; Jacques Derrida, On f/fc I^cuue^ ed. 
Thomas Dutoat and trans. DavEd Wood, John P Leavey, Jr_ and Ian McLeod 
(Stanford: Stanford University Pieas^ 1995), 6Bj Jacques Derrida^ 'How Lo 
Avcid Speaking: Denials'^ in HaroJd Coward and Toby Foshay (eds^ Ot^rnda 
and Negiitive TiieoiGsy i^ib^^y: SV[\Y riess, 1992^ 77-83. 

5- Pruyt^ts, 1 1. 

6. Ibid-, 6-7, 10-] 1. 

7. ibad, ZH 

S- On the Ncmn^, SO; Pf^iyers, Z7-S. 

9. Of} the NiWft^, Ki i]ia 69. 
10- Prayers, 6; also 11,12, 47-8, 57, 6:^- 
11. Ibid-, 113. . 

IZ- Jacques Derrida, Of Grnmmtiwfo^, trans, Gayatrl Chakravony SpSvak 
(Baltimore^ The Johns Hopkins University Press^ 1974; corrected edationjj 7 L 
13. Frayei\ 113- 

14- Ibid-, 73-56, UK, 129. 

15- Ibid-, 113. 

16- Ibid-, H6. 

17- Ibid-, B6. 

18. Tbid, 96 

19- Jacques Derrida. Thf Gift of Denthj, t^^, David Wills (Chicago: University of 
Chicago Press, 199SJ, S3-4- 

20- Prayers, 155- 

21- Ibid-, 125. 



184 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 



22. Ibid.^ 124; see tifjo Jacquizs DeFrLda^ Ttie Specters ofMtifx, trans. Pe^y Kamuf 

(New Torki Roatledge, 1994], 3L. 
2-;-i. Specters of Marx, ^1. 

24. Specters of Mtirji, 59; Gift of D^tithj 49} Jacques Derrida, Taith and KnowJ* 
edge- the Two Sources of 'Religion' at the Limits of Reason Alone'. In 
Jacques Derrlda and Gianni Vattimo (eds], Ri'Ugion {Stanford: Stanford Uni- 
versity Press, 1998), 17-18- 

25. Pmvers, 12iJ- 

26. ibcd., 99, 

27. ibid., 150- 

28- Specters of Marx, 65 _ 

29 Ibid. 

30. Pmyeis, 12S- 

31. Taith and Knowledge', 17- 
M. PriiverSf 13L 

3i\. Specters of Marx, ^6. 

34, Prayers, 1S4_ 

35. Ibid. 

:«. Ibid,, 155- 

37- Emmanuel Levinas^ 'The Trate of the Other', in Mark C. Tayior (ed.)^ Decon^ 
stnictsGU iu Context: Lit^r{7tiire and NUiosophy {Chicago: University nf Chicago 

Brei^s. 1986]. 'A46. 

38- nicGif^ofDenth.VQ. 

39. Sean Hand <ed.j, Tfie Leviim.'^ Retidtrr {Oxford: Eaackwell, 19S9>, 28- 

40. Prayers, 150- 

41. Jacques Derrida^ 'Deconstruction and the Other'^ in Richard Kearney 
ted_)j Diah^ne.'i with Cotfteuipi}rary Ca^ituieutai Tf linkers (Manchester, UK: 
Manchester University Tress, 1984J, 119- 

42. PauJ TUlcch, Tfre Coisrage to Be (New Haven. CT: Yale University Press, J 95ZJ. 
4;i. Karl Rahner, Prtiyers aud MediTalit?us iNew York" Seabury Pre^vs., 19K0)j 35. 

44. Caputo. Prayers, 12S and 150. 

45. Ibid., 128- 

46. Ibid., 148- 

47. Ibid., 96 

48. rbid., 75. 

49. [bid., 76. 

50. Derfida, 'Deconstruction and the Other^ 12C- 

51. The Gift ofDtfiilh,^:^. 
52- Ibid., 6K. 

5:i. Ibid., 68. 

54 Ibid., 69. 

55, Ibid., 70- 

56- Ibid., 71. 

57- Ibid., 85- 

58. Ibid., 86. 

59. Ibid., 7S. 

60. Ibid.. 6K- 



61- For an etalwrataon of ihe concept and morahEy of collective action as 

distinguEshed fiom those of mdiviiiijal action, aee An^ivn Kyongf^uk Mm, 
Dufle^itic of StjSv£itiot^i h^ue^ in TfieoSo^^ afU!:^intwu {Albany: State Lrni%^ef^ity 
of New York [^ress, J9S9j, 1Q4-1S. 

eZ- On the Ntmie, 46. 

63_ Dcam!imtctum in i^ NiitshcU, 13-14- 

64- Specttfvs {}fMiirx, ZZ-ii. 

SS. Ib^d., 2^' Di2comPHCtum in ij Nutshcil, 17-lH, li4-5. 

66- Richard J. Be^nstean^ 'An AlJegory of Modernity/Postmodernityi Habemias 
and Derrida', an Gar\^ E. Madison [eclj, Workin,^ through Demrfrt lEvan^Ton; 
Northwestern Unaveriiity PresSj 19^;^). 227; Thomas McCarthy, The Potitics 
of the Ineffable: Deriida's Decoiiitiuctionism'j Hif PfiihiGpliiait Fomm 21: 

1-2 {Fall-Winter, 1939-90), 146-6K. 

67- William James^ T^ef Will to B^lii^ve itfsd Otijer Essays in Popithfv Philo:SGphy 
(Hew York! Dover Publications^ 1956; originally published tiy Longmans, 
Green ti Co-, 1897), 17-19. 

6S_ For my similar critique of Emmanuel Levina?, ^t^ my Toward a Dialectic 
of Totality and Infinity: Reflections on Emmanuel Levinas'^ The Joirmiil of 
R^Stgioi? 7S:4 (October 199KJ, 571-92. 



12 

Voices in Discussion 

D.Z. Philtips 



F: Dcrrida is well received by Lhcologians, but among philosophers he 
is not so fortunate. Perhaps this is because he attacks eighteenth- 
ccsiiury rational Micolog^'H ^^ attack which extends into a eriLicLun of 
Platonic and Aristotelian metaphysics_ He talks in terms of postmodern 
Hcideggcrian rcflecnonSj and his work has been influenced by Lcvinas- 
His work can be related, with profit, to that of J.-L. Marion. 

What arc the main ohjeetions to his views? li is better to leave the 
term postmodern to itself, since It is used so loosely now. It is better (o 
talk of posL-structuratism. tn this the pbtloso[^liy of iliffl^rence is the 
main heuristic device, it falls under two denominations. One empha- 
sizes polymorphic plurality and goes back lo Nietzsche. The other goes 
Jpack to Kierkegaard and is Influenced by Lcvinas who is anything but 
postmodern. Levinas is a conservative, Jewish Rabbinical scholar- 

For Nietzsche wc are confronted by the innocent play of forces, Imth 
noble and ignoble. This is the play of necessity for which no one is 
responsible. Nazis are like waves whicli crash on the shore and break 
houses down. Some try to dcmocraiize this on the Nictzschean left. 

Nietzsche shows us what we do not want Christianity to h<i. Here we 
can be self-destructive with the notion of ^uilt. Much of the abuse is 
aimed at this tradition. 

The otlier tradition goes back to Kie^^gaard and emphasizes God as 
the wholly other to which wc are subject as the measure of truth. 
Levinas introduced ihe prophets to Paris of all places, where so many 
exotic philosophical plants ^ow. If the Bible makes sense it should make 
philosophical sciisCj and io Levinas uses Plato to emphasize the ethical 
relation to the neighbour Me sa)3 that the face of the other is the trace 
God leaves of himself as he withdi'aws from the world. Philosophers 
took notice of these Biblical categories, amon^ them Derrida. He is 



1S6 



DZ. rtiiHip^ 1&7 



seriously interested in Lcvinas in his emphasis on justice, Ehc gift 
(grace) and hospitality, the most venerable of the Nomadic virtues. 
This year he is to give a series of lectures on forgiveness. He is inter- 
ested in matters chat can he put to work. Me is not interested tn the 
philosophy of religion. 

I: I have no quarrel with F^s interpretation of Derrida, so T will go 
sLraiglil to my criticisms. 

First, iiving witli the otlier' is central In Derrida's work. It is aprdh- 
1cm which is likely to increase in our global world. No one has raised 
this problem so intensely as Derrida. Lcvinas stressed that a concern 
wUh the other cannot be reduced to sclf-ititcrcst. For Dcrrida the other 
has a self-negating transcendence^ and so purifies us of dogmatism and 
cultural particularity. So he seeks a 'religion without icllgjon'- Religions 
are criticized for not living up to this ideal. Dcrrida tends to ignore 
possibilities for self-iranslormation Vn^ithin specific faiths. Instead^ he 
criticizes them for what they caniiot be. He doesn't tell us how to 
improve them. Derrida's speculations are beyond positive law and pos- 
itive rights. So he has been accused of impotent dclitKrations, Tticse 
problems are not resolved in The Foiitics of Friendship because he has a 
fear of community, hence his emphasis on iUffereiKe. The social is 
always seen as an oppressive, exclusive singularity. Dcrrida cannot have 
a theor)^of political action. 

How do I relate Dcrrida lo liberation theology? In this latter context 
I emphasize the infinite dignity of the individual, as in the classical 
tradition. By 'totality' I mean any system of identity. It may or may not 
be oppressive depending on the attention it gives to infinity. RnalEy, 
I emphasize ^solidartty^ the mutual rcspoi^se to our dependence on 
each other. But without lotalityj informed by inhnity, this becomes an 
empty ideah 

I distinguish betwTcn the sceptic who, Ix^causc of the fear of errors 
denies truths and the pragmatist who will risk error for the sake of 
truth. Dcrrida is more like the sceptic. He flees from our difficulties and 
takes refuge in a dream of the impossible. Difference is not human, but 
angelic. 

F: I liked your paper up to a point; that point was when you beg^ 
crificfzin^ rael 1 don't recognize Dcrrida in your criticisms. He does not 
have a dream of the impossible. On the contrary, he insists that specu- 
lation should begin from where wc are. The singularity he emphasizes 
is not that of the self, but of the other. He is seriously concerned with 
justice, but it is not a goal svhich can be sj>ecified once and for all and 



188 Pfiihsnphy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

then sought after It is a iicvcrcnding ideal He is not condemning par- 
Ncular institulions^ but he is critical oi crude solutions and anxious to 
see that they are not thought to be the ideal. Our institutions are for- 
ever answerable to an unending ideaL 

C: I want to compare Derrida's emphasis on differe-i'ice with WittgcnsteiiT's 
promise to teach us differences. MieliacI Weston iii his Kierke^mmi ami 
ContuiL'ntiii P}}i}oiophy argues that ^;ietzsche, Heidegger and Dcrridan 
although avowedly anti-mctaphysieal, eannot resist the temptation to 
put some general attitude in its place- This somctliing is subiimed ahovc 
tlie differences. Do you think that is a Just accusation? 

F: Deeision in'UsMda is neither wanton nor pointless. Tlie 'suhliinc"" is 
welcomed sinee it is what we arc not. The new age is not here. VVe 
must always respond critically to the present. 

/: Isn't there a difference in the later Derrida? In his early work he 
responds to specifie texts and destabilizes them, liut now eomes a con- 
cern with justice. Why justice? Justice presupposes p^ticular institutions^ 
whereas his general position only supports destabilizatton. 

F: I don^t think the early texts arc wanton^ but he did nol think they 
coutd be made objective by closed rules. 

/: Which is why he thought Scark was so awry. 

F: Exactly. How many ways can a text be opened up? He finds as many 
as he can. But the expectation of a new^ way saves it from heing played 
around- 

G: But hasn^t an act of subversion taken place in The Gift of Death? 
1 feed my cat while thousands of other cats are starving. So it is with 
humans. So I cannot fulfil my obligatton at all if 1 start w^ith one. 1 also 
make ihe other dependent on mc. 

F: The late writings are often said to be open to this objection. But 

Derrida wants to describe a self-limiting set. What we want from a gift 
makes it Impossible. What 1 actually do is to produce a del?t of grati- 
tude in the recipient, and a feeling of jjcnerosity in myself. But his 
argument is not: therefore no gift, but a tccognition thai this is the 
human situation, a sclf-hmiting set, Derrida is telling us to understand 
this and then act - understanding our Limilalions. U we ignore the 
logic of the gift it has an unfortunate effect on us. Know what it is to 
give; know the inherent difficulty in a gift. The limitation is structural^ 

+ 

not personal. 



DZ. rtiiilip^ 189 

G: But as long as there arc cats I can't fecdn ^ilt is built in, structurally^ 
to my act- 

F; But ] must act. 

G: 1 doubt that Is his \1cw. 



F: I don't accept that 

D: Arc you saying that these insi^^lits into our limitations are better 
achieved by his philosophy than any other kind of philosophy^ say, 
Process Thought or analytic philosophy? 

F: No, I didn't mean to. But Dorrida does attack the notion of the 
autonomous subjccl. in philosophy which you find from Descartes^ 
through Kant to Husserh hi Levinas we arc called forth by the law, but 
this is not equated with reason as it is in Kant. 

B: But responding to the other is not independent of rulcSn is it?; rules 
that can bo extended in various ways la meet new situations? 

F: Derrlda has hrokcn with the Heideggerian conception of language. 
He wants to say that we must go beyond rules in recognizing liial the 
other may surprise you- You have to listen to something you didn^t sec 
coming. Tlie otiier knows something you don't- So the Messiali cannot 

turn up, for then Uiere would he no more surprises. Derrida is always 
open to a new game. 

B: Is what is to be accepted as a new game entirely up to me? 

F: No, it depends on the conditions of discourse. 

B: Tliat sounds like Korty. 

F: NOh I do not find Dcrrida's seriousness in Rdrty. 

O: Whv should niv relation to the otiier be ethical? What about sexual 
relations? 

F: Dcrrida is more poUtical than ethlcaL We'd have to look at the 
details of particular cases. Unjust laws are answerable to the demands 
of hospitality. 

F: Arcn^t the terms of the equation in Derrida too simplistic? On the 
one handj ycu have certain demands which belong to specific religious 
traditions- On the other hand, you have his emphasis on 'religion 
without reli^ion^ flow arc these to Ix: combined? There seems to be an 
un re solvable tension between thcni. 



L90 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

F: There is no reason why one shouldn't consider the relation bchvccn 

these emphases in specific contexts. He is not talking of an abstract 
impossibility. The difficulty of the oilier is always in the present. We 
must begin where we are. Derrida detests the late twentieth-century 
view of democracy^ as tliough ihc answer has arrived. What he wants 
u^ to do is lo view any situation in a critical tension between what we 
arc and what wc arc not. 



PartV 
Critical Theory 



13 

Critical Theory and Religion 



MtJ tth /ii5 Li itz-Bach umu i j 



I r - ^ 



TliQ'^Crltlcal Theory' of the Kankfurt School was conceived in parLtcular 

by its fouiidcrs Max Horkhcimer and Thcodor W. Adorno, as an 'opGn 
project': that Ls^ more a phiiosophlcalJy funded search for a theory of 
society than a unified doctrine or teaching. Il h not therefore surprising 
that the positions taken by critical theorists on Lhe question of religion 
differ significantly from one another in their details. 

hi my paper, thereforCj I wish to examine a few selected texts by pro- 
ponents of the 'Critical Theory'. 1 shall first discuss the critical impulse 
of the philosophy of Max Horklieifner from his early period in the 
19j50s (1); second, the fundamental aims and philosophical programme 
in the 'Dialectic of Enhghtenmcnt^ by Horkheimer and Adorno (2); 
third, the relation of the later critical theory of Horkheimer and Adorno 
to religion and what they called 'theology' after the Second World War 
(3> and fourthj 1 shall refer to a criticism of these general theses of 
Horkheimer by Jiii'geai Habermas (4j. 



1 



Max I'lorkhcimer In 1957 wrote- 

Critical Tlieory displaced thcolog)^ but has found no new Heaveii to 
which to point, not even an earthly Heaven. But critical theory can- 
not erase the memory of Heaven and will always be asked the way 
that leads there, as if it weren't already a discover)? that a heaven, to 

which one can point thcway^ ts none at alh^ 

This short description of his philosophical convictions makes clear the 
Importance of the theme of religion in Horkhcimer's work. It penetrates 



19J 



194 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'fii^smr m tta^ 21%i Century 

his entire thought aiid cannot be separated from his central concerns. If 
in his final creative period he was perhaps more clearly concerned with 
the object of religion than previously, It can be argued conversely, that 
the religious problematic is already closely connected with his writings 
of the 19ms. 

Horkheimer-s early work for the Zeitsihrlft fiir Sozkifforschuiig, like his pro- 
gramniatic inaugural lecture at the University of Frankfurt and his 1931 
lecture as Director of the Institute for Social Research, are characterized by 
the attempt to reflect philosophical]}^ on an empirical and at the same time 
historical conception of social research. l-iorkheimer sees 'the present situ- 
ation ot social philosophy' as the title of his lS)?j\ lecture puts It^ as char- 
acterized by an unfruitful side-by-side of positi\^stlc social science^ on 
the one hand, and a kind of social philosophy^ on the other^ which looks 
to a Uranspersonal sphere" of ideally constituted slate or humanity or a 
'value ill itself and \iews these as 'more essential, meaningfLj] and sub- 
stantiar than the empirically accessible ordinary world of the IndtviduaL 
For Horkheimer the criticisms of a positivistic philosophy modelled on 
the social sciences that were advanced by the Marburgcr neo-Kantians as 
well as by Hans Kelsen, \Iax Scheler or Nicolai Hartmann were insuffi- 
cient since they criticized neither its methodology^ nor its concept of 
facts, but rather they set them more or less constiuctivcly, more or less 
'^philosophically^' over against Ideas, essences, totalities, independent 
spheres of objective Spirit^ unities of meaning, ''national characters'" ^tc, 
which' they considered 'equally foundational - Indeed^ ""more authen- 
dc"" - elements of bclng/^ 

Horkiieinier opposes such a concept of ptiilosophy since the relation: 

between philosophical and corresponding specialized scientific dis- 
ciplines cannot be conceived as though philosophy deals with the 
really decisive problems ...while on the other side empirical research 
carries out long^ boring, individuaT studies that split up into a thou- 
sand partial questions^ culminatirig in a chaos of cotintless enclaves 
of specialists.^ 

In contrast, for the Institute for Social Research, Horkheimer pro- 
poses a programme of 'a conilnuouSr dialectical penetration and dcvel- 
opmcnt of philosophical theory and specialized scientific praxis^"^ to 
which: 



-■ •, 



philosophers^ sociologists^ economists^ historians^ and psychologists 
are brought together in permanent collaboration to undertake in 



common thai whicli can be carried out individually in the lal>oralory 
in other fields. In short, the task is to do whal all Ituc researchers 
have always done: namely, to pursue their brger philosophical ques- 
tions on tlie basis of the niosl precise scientific methods^ to revise 
and refine their questions in the course of their subst*intiye work^ 
and to develop new methods without losin;^ ^^^ht of llie larger 
context.^ 

With the concept of a dialeetical mediation of the Individual sciences 
and the philosophical question ahout the totality, Hotkheimer returns 
to some hasic elements of Hcgers philosophy, insofar as these had 
been incorporated into Marxist theory. In contrast to Georg Lukacs^ 
Horkheiiner's reception of HegeFs philosophy does not extend so far as 
to ground a materially oriented universal history and an 'absolute 
knowled^' of it. Horkhcimcr's relation to Hegel is much more deter- 
mined by tlie insight that the doctrine of identity has long broken down 
and Avith it Hcgers system of idealistic phiIosophy_ But, as Horkhcimcr 
poinls oat, 'it is easily forgotttin all of wliat it Ijuricd mth it'-^ 

For Horkheimer an accurate concept of history must t^hi as its start- 
ing point a historical-malerial analysis of human labour in history such 
as that of Marx and Engels. In his essay History imd Pj;ycholo^ pub- 
lished in 19'^2 ill the first volume of the Zeitscbrifi fiir Sozkilforsclimig, 
Horkhcimer wrote: 

Marx and Engels took up the dialectic (of Hegel) in a materialist 
sense- They remained faithful to l-legeTs bcliet in the existence of 

suprain dividual dynamic structures and tendencies in historical 
development, but rejected the belief in an independent spiritual 
power operating in history. According to them, there is nothing at 
the root of history, and nothing is expressed in history that could be 
interpreted as comprehensive meanings as unif)ing force^ as moti- 
vating Reason^ as immanent telos/ 

It Is not difficult to see in such formulations the revival of the thought 
of Marx and Engels Germaf} Jiieolog}K When Horkhetmef describes 
historical materialism as that view of history in which 'the turn from 
metaphysics to scientific theory^ is realized, he acknowledges that even 
such an accurate inlcfprctation ts vulnerable to being torn apart by 
dogmatists. Such dogmatism is always a threat to historical materialism 
as Marx understood it. Against Marxist orthodoxy Horkheimer points 
out: 'Marx insists that no insight logically prior to history offers 



196 Pfiihsnphy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%t Century 

the key to its undcrst^inding/^ Ho underscores both the continuing 
indccisivcncss and the historical condilioncdncss of a materialist view 
of historv as well as its critical function. This is evident when 
Hoikheimer^ in the face of an economic dctcrminisc view of history 
continued lo maintain that human f>eLngs are producers of the entire 
historical shape of their human life even if this takes place in a con- 
strained and irrational form. In this way, Horkheimcr shows that ;he 
economic necessity proclaimed by Critical Theory i5 not as invariant 
natural or historical law but the diagnosis of a wrong structure of soci- 
ety wliich has to be overcome, hi his programmatic article 'Traditional 
and Critical Tlicory' Horkhcinicr explained that the concept of necessity 
is not a descriptive concept but a normative one. I'liat means it presup- 
poses the idea of human autonomy as historically possible but not yet 
realized in a capitalistic economy. Here Horklieimcr returned to insights 
of Kant's philosophy of history^ holding to the idea of a future societ}^ as 
a community of free men.^ Kant's employment of reason tor tlie purpose 
of judging and grounding correct action is^ like for Hegel and Marx, 
reiransportcd into the sphere of historical deveiopmcnL HorkJieimcr 
explains that Critical Theory is linked to tlic interest of the oppressed In 
overcoming the class rule. Foi him that is the negative circumscription 
of the materialistic content of the idealistic concept of reason. 

Reason and truth are concepts that Horklieimcr^s Critical Tlieorj' docs 
not wish to do mthout, while not thereby simply returning to the 
version of these concepts worked out by Kant and HegeL Horkhcimcr is 
ne\'ertheless aware of the Inevitable problems posed to historical materi- 
alism by historical relativism and pragmatism which inform his critique 
and renunciation of metaphysics. He attempts to avoid these problems 
by holding to a negative notion of tnitli in the form of a true theory of a 
false state of affairs. Tlic model of such a thcor\^' is, as he writes in his 
1935 essay. The I^roblem of Tiuth'^ Karl Marx's systematic presentation 
and critique of the bourgeois economy- For Marx 'reason^ takes the form 
of a dialectical critique of the determinations of 'understanding'' and the 
economic categories. This process is in principle infinite since in theory 
tliere is no possibility of reconciling the contradictions which arise in 
society. Horkheimer j^oes beyoiid the theory itself and looks to the 
historicat stage when he writes that: 

the truth advanced because the human beings who possess it stand 
by it unbendingly, apply it and c^rry it through, act according to it, 
and briti^ it to povs^er against tlic resistance of reactionarVn narrow^ 
one-sided points of vicw.^"^ 



The question of the truth of thinking has now widened to include the 
problem of the iruth of historical rcality. 

Thc question ol the historical foim of rctl^ion and its claims to truth 
is discussed in a scries of essays published b)^ f-Iorkheimer in the 
Zeitsdnift fiir Sozlalfvr^chtwg against the background of liis reception of 
historical materialism. In this respect they differ from Horkhcimer's 
earlier literary essays, for instance tlie anonymously published collec- 
tion of aphorisms Diwunemnsm 1934. Ilencc Horicheimer could write 
in his short 1934 article entitled Tlioughts on Religion' that Ehc con- 
cept of God includes the idea of a better world. And he concludes that 
if justice has to be thought of as identical with God it could not be 
present in the world: 'If justice resides with God^ then it is not to be 
found in the same measure in the world. Religion is the record ot the 
wishes, desires, and accusations of counlless generations/*^ Ludwig 
Feuerbach^s theory of religion as espoused in the Essence ofReii^^mi is 
reproduced by Horkheimer in terms of an analysis of history. Marx in 
his Ifitfotiucthn to the Crlti^jiie ofHegei^s Piiilowphy ofRl^ht, had already 
referred to religion as the expression o( the suffering of the creature 
and the protest against it and so attempted to describe its relative justi- 
fication and at the same lime illusory character. Horkhcimer's own 
formulations in these years come relatively close to such jud^enicnts. 
But in contrast to Marx^ Horkheimer^s retlections on tlie illusory char- 
acter of religion do not stop there in order to move on to a critique of 
law or politics. Horkheimer holds to a notion of God which is not 
solely reducible lo psychological anthropology^ psychology or socially 
critical praxis. He writes that we find in "^God^ tlie picture of the idea of 
'a perfect justice^ but that idea can never be realized in history since a 
better society would never compensate for the suffering of tlie past. For 
HorkhcimcFH the idea of 'God' represents certainly an illusion^ but the 
concept of God at the same lime articulates the lasting universal 
human hope for fiilfihnent beyond the bounds of nature and history: 
'What distinguishes the progressive type of man from the retrogressive 
is not the refusal of the idea but the understanding of the limits set to 
its fulfilment.' ^^ 

The theoretically important idea of the 'infinite' points to a historical 
openness, indeed a metaphysical pessimism already evidenced in his 
essays from the 1930s, which is not easy to reconcile with the \farxisl 
faith in the progressive march of history. In his 1936 review of Theodor 
Haecket's book The Christuvj mitl f/f.^toy, Horkheimer notes that the 
striving for a universal justice is something about which Marxists agree 
with religious people. Horkhetmer's critique of religion in the 1930s 



19S Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'fii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

did not lead to a new dogmatism or a confession of atheism, which 
was propagated by the official Marxism of the day. Ratlier It was more a 
pari of his efforts to contribute to a philosophical critique of the limits 
of human theoretical or metaphysical knowledge in general. This 
moves his philosophy, still concerned as it is like Marx's wltli the 
capacity of human beings to change the course of historj' through 
their actions, in Lhc direction of Artliur Schopenhauer It is the dog- 
matic optimism of an 'absolute knowledge' and the human pride 
reflected in the attempt to overcome the limits of human knowledge 
which Horkheimer criticizes, in i-iegei's philosophy and in doetrinal 
religion as well as in a dogmatic understanding of Marxist theory. His 
materialism reflects the ^consciousness of the finitude of human action 
and human insight' and the 'bitterness of the death' as he formulated 
It. Precisely such know^ledge belongs to the 'essence' of materialistic 
thinking, since the indignation at the suffering of the majority of 
liuman beings originates in the experience of the uniqueness of 
human life and happiness. Horkheimer opposed 'the ideas of the resur- 
rection of the death, the last judgment and eternal life as dogmatisms' 
while nevertheless holding to thcra as expressions of the general 
human wish for 'eternal bcalitiadc'f 'universal justice and goodncss\ 
enabling a critique of the status quo and Infinitely increasing the soli- 
darity witli all living tilings^ 



2 



Horkheimcr's further philosophical de^^elopmciit is marked by the con- 
sciousness of an unavoidable sadness and an attitude of enlightened 
pessimism. This mentality mirrors the historical catastrophes of the 
twentieth century: the terror and state-oi^ganized Holocaust by National 
Socialists in Germany but also Stalin's regime and the machinery of 
annihilation of the Second World Wai which continued until the drop- 
ping of the atom bomb on Hiroshima and Nagasaki in 1.945- These 
events form the backdrop for the 'Dialectic of Enlightenment' which 
Horkheimer wrotc^ together with Thcodor W. Adorno^ while in exile in 
California. The book begins with the assertion: 



In the most general seniit of progressive thought^ the Enligiitcnment 
has ahva^^ aimed at liberating men from fear and estabhshing 
their sovereignty. Vet the fully enlightened earth radiates disaster 
triumphanL^^ 



Hence it is the intention of Max Horkhciiner and Thecxior VV. Adorno to 

Lnvcstigalc llie connection between the catastrophes of the twentieth 
century and tlie programme of Enlightenment. Mistakenly, tlie cssa^^ in 
the ■'DialecUc of EnligliteiimenL' liavc repeatedly been linked to the post- 
modern attaciv on llie modern (Cartesian! notion of the subject and the 
ideals of the European and American traditions of the Enliglitenraent-^^ 
By contrast^ Horkhciracr and Adorno arc concerned with salvaging the 
programme of tlie Enlightenment in the face of their current ambiva- 
lence and internal contradictions. Thus they write in their introductory 
chapter: 

The dilemma that faced us iti our ivorkpnjved lo be the first phenom- 
tuion for investigation: the self-destruction of tlie Enlightenment. V^ 
■arc wholly convinced - and therein lies o\ifpetitio principii - tliat social 
freedom is inseparable from enlightened tliought- >veverthetess. we 
believe that we have just as clearly recognized that the notion of this 
very way of tliinktng, no less than the actual historic forms - the 
50cial institutions - with which it is interwoven, already contains 
the seed of the reversal universally apparent today.^^ 

Therein the atJthors draw the concltision: 

If enlightenment docs not accommodate reflection on this recidivist 
clement, then it seals its own fate. If consideration of the destructive 

aspect of progress is left to its enemies, blindly pragmatized thought 
loses its transcending quality and- its relation to truthJ* 

Horkheimcr and Adorno seek to secure the relation of their thought to 
"truth^ through recourse to HegcHan philosophy: from an analysts of 
the 'Concept of Enlightenment' its inner 'dialectic' as well as its histor- 
ical and social reality is to be reconstructed. This method of intellectual 
reconstruction of central concepts ts taken from Megcl and attempts to 
encapsulate the entire historical epoch of modernity and demonstrates 
the fundamental contradictions within this concept. Hegel loo speaks 
of a conceptual unity of '"presentation and critique' and employs the 
notion of a 'detemiinaie negation'- But in contrast to Kegel - and here 
once again HorkhciiTLcr and Adorno follow Marx - they do not expect 
a 'detcrniiriaLc negation' to overcome and reconqilc ail contradictions 
in the manner of a speculative concept. 

In the fundanicntal programmatic first cliaplcr o( the Dialectic of 
Eriiighteumeyit entitled The Concept of EnUghteninent', Horkheimcr 



200 Pfiih.^ophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

and Adorno idcntif)^ three historical forms of reflection and knowledge 
which they recognize as having the potential to break through 
the blind inextricable development of the contradictory processes of 
Western raLionahty: thc^eare 'art'^ 'critical thinliing' and "religion'. Here 
too we have an analogy with Hegel and the stages of 'absolute Spirir' 
found in his Encydopeiiin}'' Vet in contrast to Hcgct, these moments do 
not form a reflectively closed wholc^ whose highest form is represented 
by philosophical thinking- As a result of their critique of Hegeln 
Horkhefmer and Adorno give a different valuation and assessment of 
these concepts from those of HegcL By 'art' tl:iey mean authentic 
^vorks of art^ which were to be found especially but not exclusively in 
Modern Art and its abstract form of representation- Commenting on 
such 'authentic' works of att^ they write; 'With the progress of enlighten- 
ment, only authentic works of art were able to avoid the mere imitalion 
of that whicl:^ already is/*'^ It is c\adent that Horkheimer and Adorno rec- 
ognize in art a claim to knowledge, in accord ivith an acknowledgement 
of the bibltcaf iitjunction prohibiting graven images: The justness of the 
image is preserved in the faithtLil pursuit of its prohibition/*^ That 
quality links modern art with the tradition of religion. It is above all 
Uiis insight into tlic Jewish tradillon thai appears to be capable of 
breaking through a false enlightenment w^hich Horkheimer and 
Adorno see in the positlvistic creed prevalent in modern scientific 
enterprise. This has become a new myth and led to an enormous 
increase in domination. In contrast, Jewish religion broke the power of 
the ancient pagan myths by their negation in the name of God: 

Jewish religion allow^s no word that would ahcvLate the despair of all 
that is mortal- It associates hope only with the prohtbilion against 
calling on what is false as God^ against invoking the finite as the 
infinite, ties as truth. The guarantee of salvation lies in the rejection 
of any l:k&lief tliat would replace it: it is knowledge obtained in the 
denunciation of illusion-^ 



These two forms of knowledge, 'art' and (Jewish! 'religion^ point the 
way to a philosophical 'critique' of the unreason of tlie positivistlc sci- 
ence and have the power to break through the system, ^the absurdity of 
a stale of affairs in which the enforced power of the system over men 
grows with eyery step that takes it out of the power of nature'.-^ This 
critique 'denounces the rationaliiy of the rational society as obsolete. 
Its necessity is illusive, no less than, the freedom of the entrepreneurs 



who ultimatdy reveal their compulsive nature in liicir inevitable wars 
and conLracts/^ 
In conclusion^ the goal of Horkhelmcrand Adorno's study is to show 

that: 

a thinkings Ln whose mechaniam of compulsive nature is reflected 
and persists, inescapably reflects Us very own self as its own forgot- 
ten nature - as a mechanism of compulsion.^^ 

This dc-mytl^oiogizatton of positivistic thinking is an expression of the 
tiopc by Horkheimcr and Adorno to transcend what they call ^thc false 
absolute' that means the principle of domination. 



After his return from exile one searches in vain in Horkheimer^s philo- 
sophical writings (oi a programmatic work expressive of his primary 
philosophical concerns. His countless essays and lectures from the 
period^ often occasional pieces dictated by Ehe demands of the 
moment, are materially closely related to his writings in the ^Dialectic 
of Enlightcnmciit'. This holds true for his personally reflective 'Notes: 
1949-1969' which despite thetr lack of systematic character are not 
without philosophical sharpness. 

In his writings after 1950 one is confronted with an increasingly 
radical episteniological scepticism and a pessimism about the prospects of 
theoretical and practical philosophy- Here one must not forget that 
Horklicimer's interest in philosophy was awakened by his early reading of 
Schopenhauer. It was only after his confrontation with Edmund Husserl 
and Jmmanuel Kant that the young I [orkheimer turned to Hegelian phi- 
losophy and its critical reception by Marx. His philosophy remained 
indebted, even in his appeal to the notion of 'critical social research"", to 
Marxian materialism, Kantian criticism and Schopenhauerian pessimism. 
Thc resulting enlightened 'sceptical niateilalism' forms the foil to his 
philosophy of religion. 

Horkheimer's concept of philosophy shows itself. In consequence of 
his critiqties of both a too narrow concept of European Enlightenment 
and of the positivism of the scipnccSj as beholden to a notion of ratio- 
nality which holds to the idea of an absolute truth is nevertheless 
in principle unattainable to finite human understanding. This corre- 
sponds to Schopenhauer's epistemologically critical insight that the 



202 Pfiih.wp!iy ofRi'lii^smr m ttn! 21%i Century 

world is appearance. The 'in itself of things - thai iSj their essence 
remains unknowable. For Horkheimer every form of metaphysics which 
makes claims to knowledge of essences is fundamenlaOy impossible 
since it docs not correspond to tlic capacilics of finite human under- 
standing. Howi^i'er HorklicLmcr sees that this epistemological scepticism 
Is subject to an objcotioit which for ^ood reason he does not wish to 
contest. Writing with a view to liis critique of knowledge he notes that 
the entire reflection on the impossibility of philosophy falls under its 
own verdict of which it itself consists.^* He admits philosophy against 
itself is impossible because it asserts the truth of that which il never- 
theless dcnies.^^ Yet this aporeric inslglit into the impossibility of 
somelhing like a final truth for philosophy. Is not itself claimed to l>e a 
final Eruth- TItat conclusion would be an 'idealistic dead-end^ a tres- 
passing of the limits and competence of finite human understanding. 
■"Can we concluded Horkheimer asksr 

that because scepticism confl^cttcts itself that some non-sceptical 
philosophy, religion or some faith is perhaps justified? No, there is 
another conclusion to be drawn: to keep silent. That which has 
always been said, is never really said, since he who ought to hear it, 
the fnfinitc One, does not hear il.'^^ 

Since Horkheimer ties the philosophical idea of a positive fulfilment of 
truth claims in human language to the attainment of ^The Infinite' but 
thinks that this is something reason can neither prove nor positively 
deny, human langtiage loses its claim to truth even while ordinary 
language and the positive sciences remain bewitched by such language. 
As he writes in his 'Notes': 

language in the emphatic sense, language that wants to claim Lruth, 
is babbling silence^ nobody speaks and language does not speak 
to anyone- Therefore nothii:ig is true. Not even that we are in the 
darkness of night fs true^ not even that it is not true, is truc.^^ 

Horkheimer interpreted the logical positivist denial of a transcendental 
meaning to the world and the binding character of truth as a sign of the 
inevitable decline of the grand tradition of European philosophy That 
this critique of positivism was not linked to the Western tradition of 
metaphysics is owing to his cpistemological sccpUcism. His scepticism 
resisted affirming that being has the same ejctcnsion as goodness and 



truthn a conviction oi Thomistic as wcH as Hegelian philosophy. In 
accord with the finite consLitulion of human bein^ and the conditions 
of human knowledge which makes (he metaphysical knowledge of 
essences impossible^ the philosopher cannot presuppose any final 
unity of being, truth and goodness. That this was done, especially in 
the neo-Plalonic tradition of metaphysics, is to be explained by the 
human desire for consolation lakcn over from leligion by philosophy. 
But the fundamental fact of conditioned finite human knowledge is 
the fact of death which is constitutive of the 'essence' of human 
knowledge. In continuity with the ancient tradition of inatcrtalisUe 
philosophyj Horkheimcr contends that his philosophy does not over- 
look human mortality. 

Kant's theoretical philosophy is for Horkhcimer in a decisive respect 
more honest than the tradition of ratlonallsllc metaphysics, against 
which Kant's ^Critique of Pure Reason' is directed. But Schopenhauer's 
metaphysical pessimism which Horkheimcr recognizes as having a 
high degree of initial plausibility in the face of the actual course of 
historical events^ trespasses the limits set by Kant's epistcniology in 
finding 'solace' in the apparent unity of the 'essence of the world as 
wLir- Schopenhauer's metaphysical pessimism turns into its opposite^ 
namely into an 'optimistic' philosopliy 

In contrast, Horkheimcr, in his 'Xotes' defends a sceptically grounded 
pessimism, which alone corresponds to the materialistic foundations of 
philosophy, liul in contrast to the essentially 'religious' pessimism of 
Arthur Schopenhauer, he insists on a 'philosophical reflection' which 
forthrightly acknowledges the limits of the realization of human striv- 
ing toward knowledge and happiness. Assertions about a reality other 
than the apparent, teal world refer to a region into which one Is in 
principle unable to entcL^** 

For Horkheimcr, the philosophical doctrine of the unknowability of 
essences or the things themselves and the impossibility of 'absolute 
knowledge' does not mean that a philosophical notion of truth should 
be replaced by a pragmatic notion of 'correctness^ Firsts maintaining 
the philosophical pursuit of "idea of absolute truth' while recognizing 
the impossibility of Its attainment, qualifies Horkheimer's thought as 
pessimistic, as if characterized by a persistent sense of sadness. 
Horkheimcr speaks, in reference to his thought of a phlTosophlcal 
Insight into the powcrlcssness of the inLellectuar.^''' He interprets this 
as the 'last and fiiia!' insight of which critical philosophy is capable 
'Ihis is the point at which materialism and serious theolog^^ coin- 
cide'-^" What Horkhcimer means by this might be explained by a 



204 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%t Century 

remark he made in reference to Paul Tlllich's notion of the concept of a 
'boundary'- In his essay 'Remembering Paul Tillich^ Horklieinicr writes: 

I have always understood the concept of boundary such that the 
philosopher should ahvays see reality as relative which mcaiiSn that 
a!l of our judgments about reality are not abi^olule and that the 
world, itself rcLalLveH presupposes an absolute chat we nevertheless 
are unable lo grasp.^^ 

Yet preciseiy his philosophical insight into the Inevitable relati'^ity of 
human knowledge presupposes the idea of an 'absolute trudi' which 
the sceptic must nevertheless regard ti.s 'pure idea'^ thai is, as beyond 
the tulftlment of finite individuals. This pessimistic or sceptical strain 
in HorkheiincE^s philosophy, viz.^ of an absolute truth as a non-^ 
relativist ic 'other' to the space-time world lias affinities with theology 
and stands in contrast both to an idealistic metaphysics and a posithns- 
tlc science. HorUicimer argues that without the idea of an absolute truth 
and Its conditions, knowledge of its opposite, that Is 'the dcsolateness of 
the human being\ is unthinkable. Ilorkheimer^s philosophy is pes- 
simistic, but not cynical- Cynical, by contrast, are those philosophical 
doctrines that beyond claiming the end of metaphysics, proclaim the 
end of 'reason^ 'the subject' and the ideas of 'humanity' and 'justice^ 

The idea of truth, to which Horkheimer holds despite his insight into 
Its unattainabtlitv takes on a critical function within scientific discourse. 
Philosophy rejects the assertion of the finite reality as an ultimate deter- 
mination and the fulfilment of the concept of t:uth. This indispensable 
and yet unattainable notion of truth is indebted at least to the concept 
and the idea of God- With the notion that the unconditioned truth cor- 
responds to the coiicept of God, Horkheimer transcends l>ehind the 
contrast between belief and denial of God^ or in his words: the false 
alternative bet"\veen theism and atheism- In the past, atheism some- 
times has been thought of as a document of freedom of spirit as 'a wit- 
ness to the inner independence and indescribable courage', but today 
theism has taken its place. And indeed, compared with atheism, theism 
has had at least one decisive advantage in terms of its iiiner conceptual 
determination- in principle, theism never allowed hatred in the name 
of God while hatred and murder can in theory coexist with and some- 
times follow from an atheistic view^ of the world. This judgement does 
not undo the injustices perpetrated in the name of God^ but it allows a 
degree of criticisin which does not seem possible for an atheistic reign 



of Icrror. Atrocities committed in the name of atheism do not necessary 
conflict with its fundamental philosopliical Icncnts. 

The concept of God like that of 'the truth itself cannot be given a 
dcfinile content, indeed Lt is fundamentally unknowable. Therefore for 
HorkhcimcF, assertions about the existence of God^ the Creator of the 
world and the !iaviour of humanity arc philosophically illcgitiniate. But 
according to Horkhctnicr within our knowledge of Ihe finite state of the 
world an idea of an InfiuUc is already presupposed. This idea gets its prac- 
tical fclcvance in the 'human desire for the totally Other' as well as in the 
polilical struggle for iusticc and a belter world. The practical relevance of 
the idea of God which totally coincides with the ideas of the good and 
the just does not concede anything to his fundamentally sceptical posi- 
tion. Horkheimer^s philosophical objection to a positive? human knowl- 
edge of God articulates the central concern of his cpistemolo^ical 
scepticism and his Schopcnhauerian and Marxist-oriented materialism, 
namely the philosophical insight into the finitudc of human knowledge, 
the limit? of reason and limits to human self-realization as a whole. 

In his principal philosophical work^ "'Negative Dialectics' published 
In 1966, Theodor W. Adorno speaks of a 'Passage to Materialism'-*^ 
which runs like a thread through his entire j^hilosophy. This turn to 
materiahsm is for Adorno a result of a successful search for the true 
form oc the objectivity of the worlds as it is realized in metaphysics and 
idealistic philosophy: The innervation that metaphj-'sics might win 
only by discarding itself applies to such other truth, and it is not the 
last among the motivations for the passage to materialism/^^ And 
Adorno does not shy away from describing his philosophical position 
In paradoxical terms: 'If negative dialectics calls for the self-reflection 
of ihinkingj the tangible implication is that If thinking is to be true - if 
It 15 to be true today, in any case - it must also he a thinking against 
Itself/'"^"* Thus for Adorno the concept of ^matter' is a place holder for a 
concept of realit)^^ ideahstic philosophy can only formulate as some- 
thing non-intellectual- for Adorno, the concept of 'nonidentily still 
obeys the measure of Identity- Emancipated from that measure^ the 
nonldcntical moments show up as matter^ or as Inseparably fused with 
material thlngs/-^^ 

This Insight allows Adoriio's passage to materialism in the sense of a 
priority of the object wtthln the mediation of Subject-Ob] ect_ This 
position agrees with Lhcolog)' Insofar as it holds to a hope in a resurrec- 
tion of the deaths. 'At its most materialistic, materialism comes to agree 
wilh theology. Its great desire would be the resurrection of the flesh, a 
desire utterly foreign to idealism, the realm of the absolute spirit. The 



206 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

perspective vanishing point of historic materialism would tac its self- 

^subUmatioiri^ the spirtt^s liberation from the prLinacy of the material 
needs in their state of fuUihncnt.^^ 



4 



hi his discussion of the philosophical development of Horkhcimcr and 
Adorno's thought since tlie 1940Sj Jurgcn HatKrmas points to some fun- 
damental difficulties and apoietic argumenLs of the so-called 'older crit- 
ical theor)''. It is primarily tliese difficulties which make Horkheimer 
and Adorno's appeal to the concepts and symbols of religion under- 
standable; novGrthclcss Hai>ermas attempts to avoid the difficulties 
involved in Horkheimer and Adorno's arguments by appealing to a 
universal pragmatics of language. As a rc5uk, Habermas comes to a dif- 
ferent conclusion about the function of icligion. hi his understanding 
'religion' is not able to compensate for the difficulties or limits of phi- 
losophy as it seems to do in the case of Horkheimer and Adorno. For 
HabermaSj 'religton' neither competes with philosophical rationaUty 
nor claims the ability to resolve tlie problems of a post-metaphysical 
tlieorv of reason. 

Habermas offers his critique of Horklicitncr's phHaophy of religion in 
his criticism of the representative essay Theism-Atheism' published In 
1^63- There Horkheimer contends that it is Vain to attempt to try to pre- 
serve absolute meaning svithout God'.^^ Habermas rejects Horkheimer's 
argumentation as inappropriate. According to Habermas, Horkhcimer's 
philosophical position Is based on the practical idea that the darkness 
which casts its long shadow upon world history should not have the 
last word. In Habermas's view^ Horkheimer thereby shifts the burden of 
explaining the historical catastrophes of the twentieth century to the 
concept of reason itself so that^ indebted to Arthur Schopenhauer as he 
is, he no longer trusts a philosophical concept of reason to he able lo 
pK>s]tivcly ground the morally good or at least the morally better act. 
SOj tn llorkheimer^s thought, it is the task of a critical theory of society 
to d&scribc historical wrongs or injustices In accordance with the view 
that historical materialism is a theory that describes successive condi- 
tions that need to be overcome, it is the task of Critical Theory to con- 
tribute to the improvement of the conditions of society by identifying 
societal evils and llieir 'determinate negation'- It is the weak point in 
Horkhcimer's argument that he doesn^t realize that the possibility^ of 
describing something as evil already presupposes the capacity to dehne 



M^itlsw.\ Lutz-Rtii-hmm^? 207 

the content of the concept of the good or to describe the differences 
belwt2C!"L ^good' and 'qviW 

Nevertheless, Habcrmas believes this typ^ of argument confronts 
Horkheiincr^s philosophiciilly funded Critical Theory of society faced 
with 3 serious dilemma. In comparison with his earlier and seemingly 
less presumpluous moral philosophy, the language about an injustice or 
wroii;^ which Is abolished through a 'determinate negation' neverthe- 
less presupposes, simply at the level of the description of just or unjust 
conditions^ the validity of a normative measure of value that must be 
philosophically explicated. However, Horkheimer, in Habermas's view, 
fundamcntaDy denies human understanding such a capacit^^ because it 
falls under the rule of an entirely formal, instrumental rationality Since 
Horkheiiner nevertheless docs not want to give up his intention to con- 
tribute to the amelioration of social conditions through a critical theory 
of soclet\^ yet no longer trusts human reason to pro\Kde a justification 
of such improved or normatlvely valid conditions. Hence Horkheimer 
inu5t according to Habcrmas, borroAV the now antiquated forms of 
rationality from a concept of theology amalgamated with an at least 
iieo-pl atonic philosophy. This protects the inheritance of an already 
obsolete forni of 'substantial reason'/*^ Even Horklieimcr sees that his 
own notion of 'objective rcason'^^ is an appeal to a form of rationality 
which had been surpassed by the critiques of eighteenth-century ratio- 
nalism, transcendental philosophy and idealism and which would 
never again gain ascendancy. Hence Horkheimer is not oblivious to the 
philosophical problems of ImplementiBig his own proposal. Yet he sees 
no alternative to such an 'anamnetic recourse to the substantial reason 
of metaphysical and rclig^ious views of lifc'^ in the attempt to search 
for an alternative to instrumental reason. Since Horkheimer does not 
have anv illusions about the inconsistcnev and fruitlessness of his 
appeal to 'objective reason', his philosophy offers an ambivalent mes- 
sage swingings as it docs, bchveen his own complete despair In reason 
and a 'return to ihe faith of his foicfathers'."*^ 

In contrast to Horkheimer and Adorno^ Habermas adheres to a con- 
cept of truth set in terms of his own language-based, pragjnatic theory 
with the goal of 'interpreting the resolution of a claim to truth under 
tlie conditions of an ideal communication situation, iliat is, in an ide- 
ally extended social and historical community'.'"^ In the context of an 
argumentative exchange between interlocutors whose goal is under- 
standing, flabcrmas maintains that assertions or practical statements 
imply validity claims which extend beyond a particular time and place. 
hi such utterances there is a 'moment of uncondttionedness' that is 



208 Pfiih.^ophy ofRi'lii^ou m ttn! 21%i Century 

■"deeply embedded in the process of underslandtiig'-^'* For Mabermas 
tlicre is in the very character of the communicative situaUoiij a Lran- 
seendence of [aiigua^c which points lo a possible understanding inchi- 
5ive of future communication partners. 

These few remarks about Hal>erraas's pragmatic interpretation of rea- 
son and truth within tlie context of his ^theory of cominunicaEive 
action' suffice to make clear that for Habeniias, in contrast to 
Horkheinier, 'post-metaphysical thinking^ does not require recourse to 
'God or an Absolute"^^ in order to preserve a 'meaning of the uncondi- 
tioned' .^^^ Rather this 'unconditioned' is immanent in the use of lan- 
guage ttself and the claims to truth and to coiiectncss implicit in the 
process of communtcative acting. Uut the 'unconditioned' only has 
cognitive import if it is 'justified before the forum of reasoned 
speeeh"^'^ or exposed to discursive scrutiny without quahficatlon. Yet 
one iTiust distinguish between what Jial>crmas means by the 'meaning 
of the unconditioned' and what Horklieimer called 'the unconditioned 
meaning^; for Habermas^ tlie failure of metaphysics since liej^el means 
that philosophy can no longer appeal to such a sense of the whole. 
Rather, this can only be mediated by religion where people provide 
comfort to each othcr^ a task philosophy cannot and does not intend 
to replace. Such consolation is that which takes 'the unavoidable and 
innocent injustice^ the contingency of misery^ loneliness^ sickness and 
death and throws a different tight on it, teaching one to bear it'.'*'' But 
in a further sense Mabermas can imagine that talk of an ^uncondi- 
tioiied meaning' without reference to God is 'vain'. In that case we are 
not concerned with the possibility of gaining and grounding a funda- 
mental normative insight, wliich Is strictly tlic task of a communica- 
tively constituted reason, but witli providing a 'motivating answer' to 
the question why we should act according to our best moral insights, 
including tlic question: wiiy be moral at all?"*'^ hi view of this funda- 
mental ethicat problem, Habermas suggests he can 'perhaps' affirm the 
indispensable 'meaning of the uncondiiioned\ explained within the 
work and through the tradition of biblical Religion-"*^ 

Translated bv Michael Parker 



Notes 

1, S^ Ma3c Horkheamerr 'Notizen 1930 bis 1969"'^ in: G^iammt'ite Schnfi^fti, 
\ol_ 6, ed. A. Schmidt and G. SchmidNoeiTr Frankfurt am Main, 1991, p. 253_ 



■MaStliws. L uiz-Bairiiimmn 209 



3 

5. 
6. 

7. 



2. Max Horkheimer, 'The Present Situaticn of Social Philoscphy and the Tasks of 

an InstElule for Social Research', in: Max HoikheEmer, JJi-'fiv-w?; nnks-iiiphy and 

Satrinf Sirience, Sek'ct^ii Etirty Writings, trans, by G.R Hunter I't ts}., Cambridge^ 

199:-^, p. 7. 

Ibid., p. 9. 

Ibid. 

Ibid. 

i'i'f Majt Horkheimcr, He^I miti ihti Pmblt-'ns lit^r Mt^tuphyiik, Frankfurt, 197 L, 

p. 90. ' ' 

Max Horkheimeij 'History and Psycholcg}'^,, In: Between PffHowptty and Social 
Science, op. ciE., p. 1 16. 
B. Ibjd. 

9. See Max Horkheimerj Traditionelle und Kriti^che Theorie'r In: Criticai Theory. 

Selected Es^ay:^, trans, by M J. O'Connelt et tii., Ne^v York, 15^95, pp. lEiS-243. 
10. Max Hcjrktieimerj 'On tfie Problem of TrutlV, in: Retwejui FliUosopliy and 

Ssmial Seieiice, op. ch., p. 19J-i. 
11_ See Max Horkheimer, 'Thoughts on Religion', in: Cfiticnt Theory. Selected 

Ess{iys, op. cit.r p, 129. 

12. Ibid., p. Ua. 

13. Horkheimer/Adorno, Diulecitc of Entigfitenmeni, traru. by John dimming^ 
New York, 1994, p. 3„ 

T4_ See. for instance, Jiirgen Habermas, Der phifamp!ji<;i-he Dhktm der Mmfenie, 
Frankfurt, 19SS, pp. O0-.S7. 

15. Horkhe imei, Adoriio, Diakciit trf Enli^hteniuentf op. tit., p. xiti. 

16. Ibid. 

17. See G.W.]'. Hegel, Encyclopaedia of tiie Philosopfiieal Si'iences m Outline, 
§S 553-77. 

IB. Horkheimei/Adorno, ibid., p. IS. 

19. Ibid., p. 24. 

20. Ibid., p. 23. 

21. Ibid., p. 38. 

22. Ibid., p. 38 f. 

23. Ibid., p. 39. 

24. See Max Horkheimer, 'Nolizen 1950 bis 1969', op. cit, p. 320. 

25. Ibid. 

26. Ibid., p. 321. 

27. Ibid. 

2B. HorkheimeT, 'Schopenhauer als Optimist', in: 'Notizen 1950 bis 1969', 

op. cit., pp. 3B7-8. 

29. Hoikheimer, 'Gegen dit Philosophte', in: 'Notizen 1930 bis 1969', op. dt., 

p 2R1 

30. Ibid. 

31. See Horkheimei", 'Erinneruiig an Paul Tidich', in: Ge^iimmiiite Sdmften, Bd. 7, 
KrankfuTt, I9SS, p. 279. 

32. Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, trans, by E.B. Ashton, New York, 
1992, p_ 192. 

33. Ibid., p. 36J f. 

34. Ibid., p. 365. 

35. Ibid., p. 193. 



2iO Pfiih.^ophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

S6, rbid., p. 207. 

37. See Max Horkheimer^ 'TJtieism and Atheism^ in" Crrf;jjz;f of fn^tmrnenti}! 

Rta'ian, trans, by M. O'Conn^Cl t'tni., Neiv York, 1974, p. 47. 

38. See jiirgen Habermas^ 'Einen unbecimg;ten Sinn zu retten ohne Gott i5t 
eiieV, in! M. Lurz-Bachmann^G. Schmid Noeir^ Kiiris^fii'i Mateiluiismus, 
Municli, 1^1, pp. 125-42. 

39. See Max Horktieimer, "Zur Krittk Jer instrumentellen Vemunft^ in : ^sss^tnr- 

iiii^iie Schfif^?!. VQ\. 6, Frankfurt/M., 1591, esp. pp. 27-74, 165-S6. 

40. Jtirgen Kabcrmas, op_ cit.. p. 134_ 

41. Ibid., p- 131. 

42. Ibid., p. 139. 
4:i. IbEd., p- 140- 

44. Ibid. 

45. Ibid., p- 141- 

46. IbLd. 

47. Ibid. 
4K. Ibid. 

49- SeeJuf^En Habermas, 'Israe! und Athen odei: Wem gehort lYie anamnelische 
Vernuj]tt?'r i^^ Diu^noseu z^tf Zeil, DusseldGrf, 1994, pp. 57-64. 



14 



Critical Theory and Religion 

Maeve Cooke 



Critical Ihcorv^ is a ihcory of society with a 'practical intent': a theory 
concerned with investigating the potentials for freedom, justice and 
happiness in actual historical social sysiems with a view to iransforniing 
them accordingly. As a normative theory of society it trolli diagnoses 
the causes of social evils and points the way towards better - more 
rational - forms of social life. This holds both for ear^v criticaJ theorists 
such as Max Horkheimer as well as for contemporary heirs to the tradi- 
tion such as JiJrgcn Habcrmas- Critical theory is thus not primarily a 
theory of knowled;^c or a theory of truth - indeed, not even primarily a 
theory of justice or of freedom - although sucli theories form an 
important part of its endeavours. Bearing in mind iLs practical orienta- 
tion towards society as a whole, my essay initially focuses on the fol- 
lowing question: what distifictive cofftnhiitfon, if any, docs religion make 
to a critieaL social theory? Here I concentrate on the work of (the early) 
Horkheimer. in the second section, I consider some points of conver- 
gence between Horkheimer and llabcrmas. Here, the problem of truth 
emerges as a potential challenge for critical theory. 



A concern with religion is evident throuj^hout Horkhcimer's writings 
although, as a number of commentators have obser\^cd, it appears to 
play a more prominent role in his later writings than in his earlier 
ones.^ Howcverj 1 leave aside questions concerning the development of 
Horkhcimer's thought in the following, histcad I want to draw atten- 
tion to the principal t'unclions that he assigns to religion and to the 
idea of God, respectively, and consider their ^itatus w^ithin his critical 



211 



212 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

theory of society- This will necessitate, in imn, ^ brief discussion of 
what he undcrslaiids by malcrialism. 

Dialectical materialism and the social contribution 
of religion 

It is striking how often religion features in Horkhcimcr's essays of 
the 19'^0s- Although only a few of these arc concerned primarily with 
the question of religion^ refeteiices to religion can be found in almost 
all of his essays on topics as diverse as the 'problem cf truth', 'philo- 
sophical anthropology^ "^matcrialism and morality'^ 'materialism and 
metaphysics', or 'egoism and the liberation movement'. It is also striking 
that these remarks are almost equally critical of religion and favourable 
to it. This is at least partly explicable In terms of his dialectical material- 
ist standpoint- In keeping %vith this standpoint, Horkheimcr assesses 
religion as either a progressive or regressive social forces depending on 
the specific functions it assumes in concrete historical circumstances. 
Since in the present context ivc are considering the question of religion's 
distinctive contribution to a critical theory of society; my focus is on its 
progressive aspects. I argue that rcligioni even when it assumes progres- 
sive social functions, either makes no distinctive contribution to critical 
social theory as conceived by liorkheimer or inakes one that is highly 
ambivalent. The idea of God, by contrast, plays a crucial role in his 
critical theory - but mainly I contend^ in a negative sense, released 
from a positive religious framework. 

Horkheimer^s assessment of the function of religion must be under- 
stood against the background of his dialectical materialism. His version 
of tbis theory owes evident debts to the thinking of Megel and Marx, It 
follows Hegel in its adoption of the method of determinate negation as 
central for the process of ascertaining truth. Determinate negation is a 
critical method that starts by exposing the one-sided and conditioned 
character ot concepts, proceeding then to re-examine and reinterpret 
these concepts in light of their limitations^ through reference to a gen- 
eral (normative) theory.- It follows Marx in its rejection of idealism. 
Materialism rejects the view that conceptually grasping the condi- 
tioned and transitory naLure of prcvaiiing ideas is synonymous with 
overcoming them. Instead it emphasizes transformatory praxis: it 
insists on the necessity and possibility of overcoming existing condi- 
tions of suffering and oppression through collective human action.^ 
However^ Horkheimcr not only follows Marx in his materialist^ praxis* 
oriented, Interpretation of the Hegelian dialectic, he also diverges from 



iWiicv^ Cookt^ 213 

Hc^cl in a second respect- In contrast to Hcgcl - and some versions of 
Marxism - he stresses that the dialectie is in principle opcn-ciidcd-"^ 
When he writes Ihat 'In materialism the dialectic Is not deemed to be 
concluded^ lie not only rejects idcaHsm: he also affirms the notion of 
a Ji^x-c^fiv^ dialectic that maintains an insurmountable discrepancy 
between human thought and reality? According to this negative inter- 
pretation of the dialectic, the progress of history is a struggle to realize 
human Ideas in praxis Ihat can ^?t■^■^:7■bc concluded. As we shall see, this 
assertion of an ineiadtcablc disjunction between concept and object is 
one reason why the idea of God is held to cinbody a moment of truth. 

The starting point for T-forkheimer^s version of dialectical materialism 
is the need for a better order of things to be achieved through transfor- 
mation of existing historical reality. This better order of things - which 
is the normative notion guiding the dialectical method of determinate 
negation - is conceived neither formally nor abstractly,^ Rather^ it is 
given a concrete content and shape by ihe interests and desires of 
actual human beings as they have been arttcutated in historical strug- 
gles to overcome suffering and oppression/ On Elorkhcimcr's reading 
of history, human beings have historically been motivated by the 
desire for justice in the sense of overcoming inequality'^ - a desire that 
has been given a universalist interpretation only under conditions of 
modernity'^ - and by a longing for liappiness and frccdoin.^*'' There can^ 
of course, be no guarantee that future generations will continue to be 
Inspired by these ainis"^ -this aspect of materialist theory is one reason 
for Horkheimcr's pessimism in his later writings. However, in the 
essavs written in the I9;^0s- Horklieimcr is confident that affcctivelv 
based motivation of this kind is widespread:'^ he discerns In Ixjurgeois 
society a moral feeling akin to love that desires the free development of 
the potcntiafitics of each and every human being, and that finds 
expression ii*^ the twin reactions of sympathy for ncediness and suffer- 
ing and a politics aimed at the happiness of human beings in gencraL^^ 

Dialectical materialism is primarily a theory of transformalory praxis. 
Nonetheless, its view of knowledge as guided by human interests, 
which both arise out of, and iiave the power to transform, historical real- 
ity, has implications for the perspective It takes on religion. On the 
dialectical materialist view, the reciprocal conditioning of knowledge 
and reality has a double aspect! on the one hand, it has a gerealogicat 
aspect in that it refers to the origins of concepts aaid theories in iiistori- 
cally specific social constellations; on the other hand, it has a rwrmatsve 
aspect^ for it requires ideas and theories to respond appropriately to the 
fhistorically specific) interests and desires of human beings, [f we keep 



2i4 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

these two aspects distinct wc can sec that dialectical matcilalism docs 

not reduce the spiritual to the materialj even though it often gives a 
niaterialist explanation of the genesis and development of religious 
(and moral) beliefs and practices- For example^ Horkhetnier on occa- 
sion offers a materialist account of the historical connection bchvecn 
icceping promises and llie econoniic relations of capitalisnij^'^ bclween 
the modern conception of God and the capitalist principle of 
exchange,'^ and between religious faith and the failure to transform 
undesirable social structures^'^ importantly, however, he distinguishes 
between a materialist account of the hlslarical roots of morality and reli- 
gion and the question of the vaiue of the beliefs and practices he men- 
tions. For florliheimei:, the value or significance of any ideaSn ptlnciples, 
theories, knowledge, and so on depends on the overall state of society 
and on the concrete situation to which they belong. ^'" More fundamen- 
tally, as we have seen, the ultimate point of reference for determining 
value or significance is a normative, htsiorically grounded, theory of 
human interests and desires, and of the kind of social structure deemed 
appiopriate for their satisfaction.^^ 

■It is clear from the foregoing, therefore, that^ according to 
Horicheimer^s materialist view, there can be no obstruct answer to the 
question of whether religious faith is a positive or nej;ative social force. 
The value ot significance of religious beliefs and practices always 
depends on the historically specific social situation in wliich they are 
formulated. For this reason, it comes as no surprise that in his various 
writings Horkheimer both criticizes relif^ion and draws attention to its 
positive potentials. For example, he is critical of religion insofar as it plays 
down the importance of insight into the earthly order of things (thus rel- 
egating social problems to second place), by lurning the minds of human 
beings towards a more essential order.** Or^ again^ he questions Christian 
claims to selflessness, arguing that supposedly selEless Christians are in 
fact more egoistic than atheistic freedom fighters who, by renouncing 
tlie hope ot reivard in an afterlife, are willing to sacrifice their lives 
for the good of human beings in generaL^** In addition, he criticizes 
ChrisLianlty's unwillingness to acknowledge the brutality that has been 
part of human nature historically; instead it has justified its own brutal 
acts through appeal lo the 'name of Cod", leading to a repression of 
brutality rather than an attempt to deal with it rationally_^^ On the 
other hand, Horkheimer acknowledges that atheism can tic sympto- 
matic of a kind of Intellectual passivity that fails to recognize what is 
ivrong with the bourgeois social order and lacks any desire to change 



Lt.^^ Implicit in this assessment of atheism is the hasic yardstick used by 
Horkhelmcr to measure the social contribution of rcJigton. 

As he sees itn rcll^on can be regarded as a positive social force on 
tivo main couiils. The first has to do with its moral message, the sec- 
ond with its orientation cowards an idea of the absolute. 

Keligion's moral message 

Religion is a progressive social force insofar as it preaches a moral message 
of human dignlLy and universal solidarity thai inspires ciiticisni of pre- 
vailing suffering and oppression. For Horkhclmer, the proclamation of 
the infinite value of the human person^ of the innate rights of the indi- 
vidual, Lhe fight against ideologies of race, nation and 'Fuhrertum', are 
part of a humanistic message propagated by some strands of Christianity 
that can motivate social struggle for a better society.^-^ It should be noted 
here that Horkheimcr distances himself from the spiritual fiiatifiaitiim 
offered m support of religiously motivated messages of human dignity 
and solidarity, Insisting that the struggle for a better order of things has 
no need of appeals to absolute mcanlng^"^ or to an absolute demand 
{Fortknufs) upon human beings- ^'^ He sees 'man's striving for happiness 
[as] a natural fact requiring no justification'.^ feelings of revulsion 
against, and solidarity \vith, suffering and oppression are sufficient - feel- 
ings that neither require nor permit justillcatlon-^^ Indeed^ Horkhcinier 
is emphatic that morality cannot be justifted - neither through intu- 
ition nor through arguments.^ As he sees It^ nil value judgments are 
unfounded.^^ There are no binding moral commands: 'Materiahsm dis- 
cerns no authority transcending human beings that could distinguish 
between helpfulness and greed for profit, goodness and brutality^ 
covetousness and seif-sacriflce.^^'^ All religious attempts to find a divine 
justification of morality arc thus ideologtcaL Nonetheless, Horkheitner 
recognizes that under certain circumstances religious messages can 
serve to reinforce the desire for happiness and feelings of solidarity 
with suffering, thereby strengtheniiig the incentive for social transfor- 
mation- In such situations a temporary alliance between materialist 
thinkers and religious thinkers may be desirable - but only insofar as 
both aim for a better society.-^^ For our present purposes^ two points are 
particularly fele\^ant. First of aJlp religion's progressive social function is 
conditiofial: the value of its moral messag-.- depends on whether or not 
It links up with the above-mentioned feeiings to inspire transformatory 
praxis. In Horkheiiner^s view^ this link is purely contingent for^ like 
every Idealistic philosophy, religious Ideas can easily Justifj^ any kimi of 



2i6 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

attitude to existing society - a critical or an apologcllc, a reactionary or 

a rebellious one.-^^ Second, religion is ftfiaceiibie as the vehicle of the 
moral message of universal human dignity and soUdariiy. Even if^ his- 
torically, religion has been one of the most powerful means of convey- 
ing this message^ the truth of the message is dependent on religion 
neither for its justification nor for lis dissemination. As we have seen^ 
Horkheimcr holds thai molality cannot be justified, hi addition^ tliere 
Is nothin;^ about religion that makes it inherently belter suited than 
non-religious belief systems to act as a vehicle for moral ideas; indeed^ 
Its intrinsic idealistic clement makes it kss suited to this La^k than 
materialism Is. When^ in 19.^5, Horkheimcr writes that, today, 'good 
wIIIh solidarity with misery and the stri\1iig for a better world have cast 
off their religious mantle'^ he clearly approves of the development.^^ 

Reliyiuii's orit:ntatioii tawards tht idta of God 

Religion docs, however^ have one distinctive characteristic - a feature 
pcculiai to religious belief - that makes it a potejitlally progressive social 
force. This is its orientation towards the idea of God, Unfortunately, it is 
precisely this characteristic thai makes it equally a potential force for 
social regre!^j;fO!i. Horkheimcr asserts an intiinate connection between 
the idea of God and the idea of the absolute: that ISj projections of 
absolute meaning, final knowledge, perfect justice, ultimate truth and 
so on. There is an oft-cited phrase from his later writings that runs: 
'Without God one will try in vain to preserve absolute nieanin;^/'^ For 
the early Horkheimcr, at teast, the relationship between materialism 
and absolute meaning is highly ambivalent; furthermore, his approval 
of the idea of God, insofar as it is unconditional, is an approval of a 
negatively construed idea of God that is essentially non-religious. 

From the point of view of Horkheimer's critical social theory^ the 
idea of the absolute is both desirable and dangerous. On the one hand, 
the idea of the absolute expresses the longing of human beings for 
perfection - a longing that is the Utopian counterpart to the feelings 
(of desire for happiness or of solidarity with suffering] that Horkheimcr 
presents as historically articulated psychological attributes of human 
bettigs.;^^ it is the idea of an alternative, better order of things: 'For a 
long time the concept of God preserved the idea that there are alterna- 
tive standards to those that find expression In the operations of nature 
and society.,- Religion records the wishes, desires and proLests of 
countless generations/^^ Even materialists - who know that the idea of 
perfection is a potentially ideological illusion - long for eternal, perfect 



M^t\^ Cookt^ 217 

justice for all human bcin^s.^^ The uiidcflyin^ impulse towards tran- 
scending the given - or even the possible - in thought is regarded by 
Horkhcimer as part of what is to be human (which, of course^ is a 
historical caLej^ory).-^'^ As he sees it, wliat distinguishes the progres- 
s!vc type of liuraan being from the retrogressive one is not rejection 
of visions of transcendence but rather recognition tliat perfection 
can never be achieved/^^ ThuSn for example^ like Walter Benjamin, 
Horkhehner maintains that perfect justice can never be realized in the 
worlds for even if contemporary injustice were to give way to a more 
lust social order, the misery of bygone generations would not have 
been made good and the suffering of the rest of nature would still 
remain."^' In conlrasL to religious thinkerSj materialists acknowledge 
that the demand for perfection can never be fulfilled; Horkheimcr 
maintains that this accounts for a certain melancholy discernible in 
materialist writings, while insisting that melancholy feelings do not 
constitute a reason for continuing to embrace the Illusion.'^" At least in 
liis early writings, Horkheimcr holds that materialists must acknowl- 
edge the tllusionary charaetcr of their longing for perfection, retaining 
only tbe valuable impulse at the heart of it- This is the impulse towards 
social struggle to overcome the imperfections of existing social reality. 

However, the idea of the absolute is also an illusion that is poten- 
tially ideological and dangerous. In affirming the idea of salvation in 
the hereafter, it directs attention away from suffering and oppression 
in concrete social reality and runs the risk of making religion a cog in 
the wheel of the totalisttc state [totaier Staat)^^ Furthermore, the idea 
of the absolute as a meaningful object of human knowledge rests on the 
assumption of a possible reconciliation between concept and object 
that effects a closure of the dialectical process of history. To be sure, the 
idea of God can also prevent closure. As we shall see, when integrated 
within a materialist theory, the idea of the absolute is precisely the idea 
that there is no end-point of history. Paradoxically, how^evcr, the idea 
of God contains a moment of truth only when it is construed nega- 
tively and released from its connection with positive religious beliefs, 
rituals and practices. 

Again, two points should be emphasized here. The first is that, for 
Horkhelmet, the value of the religious idea of God is ^onditioiuii: it is 
dependent on whether the idea of an alternative to the existing order 
translates into actual transformatory social action. To be sure, under 
certain social conditions ffor instancen twentieth-century consumer 
capitalism) feelings of solidarity with suffering and desire for happi- 
ness, which are the main motivation for transformatory praxis, may 



218 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

wane or even disappear. In such situations the religious idea of God 
cannol easily connect up with these feelings^ and struggle to overcome 
suffering and oppression is unlikely to result. Even here^ however, reli- 
gion's usefulness remains linked to the idea of tiansforinatory struggle^ 
for the religious idea of God is valuable only insofar as it keeps alive 
the insight that an aiternativc to the existing social order is a possibil- 
ity for human action.^^ The second point is that the religious idea of 
God, although it expresses a genumc human longing for eternity and 
pcffection, is an ilhmion. Unlike the content of reli^on's moral mes- 
sage, the religious idea of God has an miiereiitly idealistic element that 
makes it ideological- This Is the cause of its ambivalence. It is because it 
is so ambivalent that Horkheimer advises maictialists to recognize that 
their longing for the absolute cannot be satisfied. They should relin- 
quish the illusion^ retaining only its fruitful impulse: the need for a 
dynamic transcending of the existing order through transformatory 
prajcis. 

1 have suggested that, for Horkheimer the ideological character of 
the religious idea of God IhrcaLens to obscure its moment of validity. 
In his vicWh in order to presence its valid insight the idea of God has to 
be released from its positive religious framework. Only as a negatively 
construed, non-religious Idea of the absolute does it play a central role 
in Horkhcimer's dialectical materialism. To grasp this role we must take 
a brief look at his theory of truth. 

Ilorkhtitner's theory t>f truth 

According to this theory^ truth can never be defined in abstraction 
from the historically arliculated interests and desires of human beings: 
truth is always historically conditioned^ it is never abstract or timeless; 
furthermore, the process of cognition includes actual historical action 
just as much as experience and understanding.^"* Horkhelmer's theory 
of truLh is guided by this emphasis on historically based UiLerestSn 
desires and actions and has two important components- The first of 
these Is tlic notion of 'cor^obc^ration■' {BemHwuns), the second is the 
method of determinate negation. 

The pragmatist idea of Bemihnms - the view that something Is irue 
only insofar as it can be corroborated, in the sense of 'proves its worthy 
'turns out to be irue'^-'' - plays a central role in Horklicimer's materialist 
theory.^ With its emphasis on concrete historical action and Its refer- 
ence to human interests and desires^ it is easy to see why this idea is 
congenial to materialism. Horkheimer refers to the American pragmatist 



iVfcTCVf Cookf 219 

philosophers John Dcwcy and William James, while acknowledging that 

the idea of Ik^wiiiimn^ goes back much furllier In the recent German 
tradition he ciles Goethe and Nietzsche as proponents of it: both regard 
something as itue only insofar as It proves to be fmttt'ul^ connects up 
with other true beliefs and is life-enhancing.^^ Horkhetmer, too, insists 
that ttie verification and truth of ideas pertaining to human beings and 
social orders docs not simplj^ consist in laboratory experiments or in 
research activity but in historical struggles in which convictions play 
an essential role.'^'^ He maintains ihat 'so lon^ as experiences gained 
through perception and Inference, methodical research and historical 
events^ everyday work and political struggles, withstand the cognitive 
tests available at any given time, they are irue/^^ He sees the notion of 
Bewiihnwg as particularly important for materialist theory in that it 
acts as a weapon against all forms of myslictsm: it attacks the thesis of 
a transcendent, superhuman truth that, instead of being accessible in 
principle to experience and praxis, remains iIk- preserve of the revealed 
knowledge of a chosen few_^ Despite the clear affinities between this 
aspect of materialist theory and the American piagmaLtsts, however, 
Horkheimer underscores a fundamental distinction. As he sees it, con- 
temporary pragmalists such as Dewey and James hold a view of social 
reality that is too harmonious. He attributes to them a boundless con- 
fidence in the world as it actually exists.^^ Far from constituting the 
theory's organizing principle, the need for change, if it is perceived at 
all, is seen as a subjective preference.^^ I-rom the point of view of male- 
rialism, the crucial dcfictency of contemporary pragmatism is Its lack 
of reference to a general (normative) theory of society-^-^ Such a theory 
Is necessary if the notion of Bewiihmng is to avoid the twin dangers of 
subiectivism and uncritical affirmation of the status quo. for this reason, 
Horkheimer joins the idea of Bewiihrtmg to the dialectical method. 

As WQ have seen, this operates by way of dcLcrminate negation. The 
dialectical materialist starts with the conceptual principles and stan- 
dards oi an object, unfolding their implications and consequences. It 
then re-examines and reassesses the object in light of these implica- 
tions and consequences. The result Is a new understanding of the 
object in which the original image of the object is transcended and the 
object itself is brought into flux- As Morkhcimer (with Adorno) formu- 
lates it detcTininate negation rejects defective ideas of the absolute by 
' interpreting every image as writing' - by showing how the admission 
of its falsity is to be read in the lines of Its features. ^^ This process of 
critical examination and reinlerpretation of concepts is guided by a 
gencTal theory, in Horkhcimcr's case, the normative component of the 



220 Pfiih.^ophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

theory is derived from an account of human interests and desires, as 
these have been Ekrticulatcd hislorically.-^^ As we have also secn^ this 
theory is progrcssiye but open-ended: absolute knowledge - and, in 
consequence^ an ciidpoint of history - is inconceivable, l-loweveip 
although Horkheimer, at least in his early writings, rcjccis the idea of 
absolute knowledge as an achievable - or even meaningful - goal of 
human action^ the idea of the absolute does play a role in his negative 
dialectics. 

Absolute knowledge is inconceivable for human beings and unat- 
tainable through human action. As such it is not a meaningful goal for 
materialists, Nonetheless^ despite its [llusory (and^ as we have seen, 
potentially ideological) character, it plays a role in materialist theory. 
Its significance is that it marks the impossibility of closure. The essen- 
tial open-en dcdness of the progress of history means that human 
beings^ desire to overcome the limitations of their given historical con- 
dition through transformaiory praxis can never be satisl'ied. hi contrast 
to religious thinking, in which the idea of the absolute signifies the^ 
possibility of eternal^ perfect truth, jusUcCn or meaning, tt has a nega- 
tivCn critical, function in materialist thinking, [n illustration 
tlorkheimer gives the example of the Jewish prohibition against nam- 
ing the absolute with names: the 'prohibition against calhng on what 
is false as God^ against invoking the finite as the infinite^ lies as 
truth'.^*" Thus, tlie idea of God as it functions within Horkheimcr's ver- 
sion of dialectical materialism is a negative image thai can be described 
as religious only in a derivative sense. More precisely^ despite its reli- 
gious origins, it can be described as a negatively construed, non- 
religious idea of God insofar as it lacks the framework of positive belief 
and concrete rituals and practices in v%i"jich it has always bccti embed- 
ded in the main religious traditions- 
Summary 

Summarizing, it can tae seen that religion either makes no distinctive 

contribution to a critical theory of society as conceived by Horkhciimer 
or elae. one that is highly ambivalent- Although under certain condi- 
tions it may assume the role of a progressive social force, its value and 
significance is continj^cnt on a number of factors. In addition, it is 
rtplaceabJe by non-religious kinds of beliefs a^ a vehicle for progressive 
social action. Finallyn it caii just as easily inhibit the struggle for more 
rational forms of social life as promote it. By contrast^ an idea of God 
plays a crucial role In his critical social theory insofar as it marks the 



Mtiew Cooke 221 

impossibntly of closure^ theretay testifying to the need for iicvcr-cnding 

struggle to achieve a better order of things. Due to the inherently idco- 
lo^cal character of religious interpretations of Ihc idea of the absolute^ 
however^ this idea is most useful when it is released from its religious 
framework and understood in a purely negative, critical way. 

Habertiias's critique of Ilorkheimfr's idea of God 

h has been argued, howe^'er, that the idea of God fulfils positive func- 
tions in Horkheimer's later writings. The later Morkheinicr, it is claimed, 
asserts a connection between absolute ^'alidity and unconditional 
meaning and the idea of God as arbiter of validity and bestower of 
such meaning- Habermas, for example^ reads the later Horkhelmer in 
tills way. As a result, he accuses him of bad utopianism. 

Habermas criticizes the role played by rctigion in Horkheimcr's latei 
work. He attributes to him the position that truth and meaning have a 
necessary connection with the idea of God. He takes this idea to com- 
prise at least two positive componcnts.^-^ 

The first of these is the idea of God as arbiter of truth (understood as 
validity in general). As flabermas reads the later Horkheimern when 
critical theory loses its basis in the philosophy of history and when 
reason in its context-transcendent sense has been eclipsed completely 
by instrumental reason, religion remains as the sole authority that^ if 
only it were recognized as such, would permit distinction between 
what is true and what is false, betivecn what is moral and what is 
immoral.^" Thus, oil llabermas^s reading, the later Morkheinicr anchors 
truth (including moral truth) tmttfhglaUly in a divine power^^ The 
second component is the idea of God as beslower of comfort or conso- 
lation:^^ the idea of God, when construed in a positive A-vay as salva- 
tion, draws togelher the disparate elements of human life to form a 
meaningful totality; its integrating power serves to reassure human 
beings that life is ultimately meaningtuL^^ Again, when critical theory 
can no longer find potentials for transforinatory social struggles in the 
philosophy of history and rationality is reduced to iiistrumental reason^ 
religion remaisis as the sole authority that mi^it be able to give a 
meaning lo life beyond that of mere self-preservaiion.*'^ 

On Habcrmas^s reading, Horkhcimer is guilty of bad utopianism.^^ 
He regards his recourse to a positive idqa of God as an escape from 
history to messianic visions, comparing it to Adorno's messianic inter- 
pretation of the truLh of ait. For Adorno the Utopian content of the truth 
of art preserves a form of knowledge that, because it is dependent for 



222 PfjitD.^ophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%t Century 

its iFansfonnatory power on imcrprctation by pliilosophic^Ll reason^ 
constitutes a genuine yet impotant alternative to ihe iiistrunicnlal ratio- 
nality pervading all aspects of social life In the contemporary world-^^ 
Such utopianisni is bad utopianism to the extent thai it explodes the 
contiiiuuin of historj^: religion or art arc assigned a purely messianic 
power for rcdempLion thai has no roots in the concrete social piaellces 
of real historical human beings, Such a notion of redemptive reason is 
aporctic insofar as it fails to link up with reason as embodied in the 
historical world of speech and action. The difficulties arising from this 
view of reason conslUtite Uie main reason for Hahermas's endeavour 
to lead critical theory out of what he sees as a theoretical impasse - 
an impasse into winch It was led by Horfcheimer and Adorno with ihctr 
jointly written Dialectic of EtiUghtei^ment.^^ Once Horklieinier and 
Adorno; 

'lost their his tori co-philosophical faiLh in the rational potential of 
bourgeois culture which was to be set free in social movements 
under tlic pressure of developed forces of production.., the principal 
'i^vcr' of the tiicory was also lost-.. instrumental reason, having 
become totals embodies itself in totalitarian societ)^. With this the 
classical form of critical theory fell apart/^^ 

In response to this collapse, Habermas attempts to show that a poten- 
tial for non-tnstrunicnlal rationality is inherent in the real historical 
world of human speech and action; his strategy initially lakes the form 
of a theory of knowledge and human intere5ts,'^^ and suhsequently that 
of a linguistic thcor)=': the programme of formal pragmatLcs.^^ 

By contrast with what he sees as Horkheinicr's anchoring of reason in 
the di\ine^ Habermas defends the possibility of a notion of reason 
anchored in everyday communication, whose context-ltansccnding 
power derives from the necessary presuppositions of discursive practices 
that have iheir basis in the everyday linguistic Ix^haviour of historically 
situated agents. In his tiew, such a conception of communicative ratio- 
nality preserves the meaning of the absolute without recourse to 
metaphysics. ^^ Its transcendent character is a transcendence not from 
and into the Beyond^ but a transcendence from within and into the 
lifeworld.^fl 

Insofar as his reading of him is corrcctj Ilabermas's rejection of the 
later Horbheimer's position is understandable- From the point of view 
of a materialist social theory concerned with bringing about more 
rational forms of human life, the connection of truth and meaning 



with a positively construed idea of God is potentially risky. One possible 
danger is that the truth of the theory^, having lost its empirical anchor 
In historically articulated human desires^ needs and feelings, might 
become accessible only to religious believers. Another is thai appeal to 
a positively construed idea of the absolute might encourage belief that 
the progress of history is divinely guaranteed, thus inducing passivity 
and impeding transformatory social praxis. Much depends, however^ 
on the precise Interpretation that normative social theory gives to a 
positively construed idea of God. For example^ it makes an important 
difference whether kmtwiai^e of the divine will or being is conceived as 
subject to the constraints of history and context. For the assumption 
that the hand of God guides the progress of history is readily compati- 
ble with the view that human beings gain knowledge of God's guiding 
hand only by way of essentially fallible processes of interpretation. 
It also makes a difference whether or not free will is attributed to 
human beings- For the above assumption is equally compatible with 
the view that human beings have the freedom to disregard the divine 
guidance offticd/^ For ibis reason^ it is relatively unimportant whether 
Habermas's reading of Horkheimcr is the most plausible one.'^ The 
point is ihat even a positively construed idea of the absolute docs not 
imply that human beings can have absolute knowledge of it; nor does 
it imply that the progress of history is guaranteed independent of 
human agency, 



Habernias's critical social theory shares with Horkheimcr the practical 

aim of bringing about more rational forms of human life. It also shates 
one central element of what Habermas refers to as the postmetaphyisical 
impulse. This is Its concern to examine the possibilities for a better life 
for human beings wrthont relying primarily on philosophical insight 
for justification of ihc enterprise: for both, philosophy has lost its 
traditional status as a mode of knowledge w^th special insight into the 
nature of ihe hunian/-^ Despite tlieir common aim and overlapping 
strategy, however, Ihe tW'O projects differ in a number of crucial ways- 
For example, despite a shared emphasis on the need for cooperation 
with the social sciences/^ Horkheimer and Habermas pursue different 
strategics when it comes to finding an alternative mode of grounding 
for their theory. Whereas Horkheimer, as we have seen, derives the 
normative basis for his critical theory from human Interests and desires 
as articulated over the course of history in social stmggles, Habermas 



224 Phih.'iophy ofRi'fii^oir m tta^ 21%i Century 

hopes that the ration^il rcccnstruction of everyday linguistic behaviour 
will pro\ide a norinaLive underpinning for his theory/^ Since a full 
exploration of the various points of divergence is beyond the scope of 
the present chapter^ my discussion focuses primarily on some points of 
convergence and divergence between Horklieimer and Haherinas with 
respect to religion and the idea of the absolute_ I first show how Haber- 
mas^ like HorkhcimciH maintains a connection between Ihc idea of 
truth and a negatively construed idea of absolute- Unlike liorkhciiner, 
however, Habcrmas insists that it is also possible and desirable to 
connect truth with a positively comtmeil yvt pasttudaphysknl Idea of 
tlie absolute. J argue that Habcrmas^s attempt to salvage a postmeta- 
physical conception of the positive aspect of truth is not succcsstuL 
! then draw attcn tion to some poin ts of agrc einen t between 
Horkheimer and Habermas concerning the question of the validity of 
religious ideas. However, here loo there is an important disagrcemcnt. 
Unlike MorkhcimeiH Maberinas concedes ihe possibility of religious 
truth. I argue, hoivever, that aecommodatins such a notion would entail 
substanlial levislon of his formal pragmatic theory of validity elaims. 

Habennas's tlitorv of truth 

Discussion of Habermas^s theory of truth is hampered by the fact that 

he has substantially amended the thcor^^ of truth which he presented 
in his 1973 essay^ 'Wahrheitstheorien\ without having fully developed 
a new, revised vcrsion7^ However, some of his recent essays cai:i be 
seen as part of an endeavour to make good this deficiency. -^^ For our 
present purposes^ it is especially important that Habermas continues to 
emphasize the ditfcrenee between justification and truth.^* fo? exam- 
ple, in a recent critique of Richard Rorty^ ffabeimas associates liimself 
with korly's pragmatist understanding of truth, wbile accusing him of 
a problematic naturalization of it7^ Rorty is criticized for reducing 
truth to justiflcalionH thus losing sight of the potential power of 
validity claims to explode actual contexts of justification. Habermas, by 
contrast, wants to hold onto the moment of 'uncondltionality" {Unbeii~ 
h^thelt) that he regards as inherent in the idea of truth, while retaining 
an internal relation bcnvcen truth and justifiability. Habermas's aim, in 
other words, is to work out a theory of tiuth that is inherently pra^- 
nialic yet relalns the notion of trutb as a claim to 'unconditionality' 
that reaches beyond all the evidence available to us at any given time. 
Although his emphasis on the unconditional nature of truth has 
remained unaltered, Habermas has recently moved away from his 



wcH-known account of truth as idealized rcitional iicccptability.^" He 
now proposes a view of truth as a concept that has a 'J^^us-facc\ On 
this understanding, the concept of truth lias two aspects: a discursive 
one and a pra^Jiiatic, lifeworld one. On the one hand^ truth is the 
concern of participants in certain kinds of rational discourse who are 
guidtd by the idc*i lliat a proposition, if truc^ would withstand any 
attempts to refute it under idea! justificatoty conditions. On the ether 
hand, truth is a pragmatic presupposition of participants in everyday 
communicative practices in the hfcworld who are guided by tlie need 
for behavioural certaintv. Ttuth's "Janus-face' tcfers to tlie dvnamic 
interplay between everyday behavioural certainties and the process of 
cntLcal rational discus^iion of tliese certainties once they fail to prove 
reliable as a basis for action in the lifeworld; the fallible results of such 
processes ol rational discussion ('discourses') are fed back as 'truths' 
into the eveiyday communicative practices of the lifeworld. They then 
provide a reliable basis fot action until, for contin;^ent empirical 
reasons, they no longer ''lA^ork' - that is, no ton^cr prove their truth 
{skh bi'waluiui) by being proof against disappointment - and have to be 
reassessed discursively in the light of the new evidence and insight. 

The idea of truth as a Janus-faced concept is supposed to show wliy 
truth is distinct from justification. It is helpful here to distinguish 
between tsvo aspects of Habetmas's idea of truth as justifLcation-tcan- 
scendent^^ Tlic first aspect is its c^u^oinin' function: the concept of 
truth warns us that even propositions that are justified under the best 
possible argumentative conditions may turn out to be fahc. Here, the 
context-transccndcnl power of truth is interpreted iiegatiwSy as a warn- 
ing about the fallibility of knowledge. The second aspect is the sense of 
uucofuUthimlity we attach to truth: truth is a property that cannot be 
lost.^^ Here, the context-transcendent powder of truth is interpreted 
positively as the idea of perfection. One advantage of this distinction 
hct^vccn a positive and negative aspect of Habermas's idea of the 
justification-transcendent character of trut^ Is that it enables us to sec 
clearly how his coneept converges with^ and diverges from, the nega- 
tive and positive intetpa'etatlons of the idea of the absolute offered by 
liorkheimer 

There are evident links between Hotkheimer's defence of the idea of 
God in its negative, non-rcligEous interpretation and Hahermas's 
defence of the 'cautionary' function of the truth predicate. This is one 
of the main agreements between Horkheimer and Habermas as regards 
the function of the concept of truth. On my readings both theorists 
uphold a negative interpretation of the idea of the absolute. For 



226 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^o}r m tto! 21%i Century 

Horkhcimcr, a negatively construed idea ol God reminds us of the 

42ssentJal open-cndcdiiess of the diatectLcal process and marks the 
ImpossLbLliry of closure. For Hatacrmas^ the 'cauiionary' use of tlic truth 
predicate u^arns us that even lationally justified propositions may turn 
out to be false^ slgnif\'ing the fallibihty of human knowledge. lioll^i 
agree, Lhercforc, that Che concept ol Lculh reminds us of human imper- 
fection, liut there is also an important point of c^hagrecmcnt. This con- 
cerns truth in its positive aspcct. 

I have attributed to Horkheimer the view that, in its positive inter- 
pretation, the idea of the absolute promises perfecLLon. 1 Lhen argued 
that - at least in his early writings - he ultimately rejects a positive 
interpretation of Che Idea of the absolute on the grounds that It is iilu- 
sory and potentially ideological. There are evident links between 
Horkhcimcr's idea of [lie absolute as perfection and liatacrmas's idea of 
'unconditionality'- However, whereas Horkheimer thinks the dangers 
of the idea of perfection outweigh its ackno^'vtedgcd attractions and 
merits, Habcrmas proposes a poslmetaphysical interpretation of this 
idea. But even Horkheimer^s rejection of a positively construed concep- 
tion of truth is not straightforward- As we have seen, tie is deeply 
ambivalent about the idea of the absolute as perfection. Althoughj at 
least in his early writings, he ultimately recommends that materialists 
relinquish a positively construed idea of the absolute on grounds of 
Its illusory, potentially Ideological character, he fully acknowledges the 
attraction of the idea: even materialists, he writes, long foi eternal, perfect 
justice for all human beings. This longing expresses an impulse towards 
transcending the given that is pan of what it means to be human and 
can have positive, trans formatory, social effects. Horkheimer^s ambiva- 
lence here suggests that he would welcome the possihlliLy of a 
non-illusory - and^ for him^ this means materialist - conception of the 
absolute In its positive aspect. Habcrmas's poslmetaphysical tnterprcta- 
tioD of the idea of 'unconditionalitj^' can be regarded as an attempt to 
pro\rtde such a conception. 

As we knoWj Habcrmas claims that the idea of the absolute must be 
conceived as ''transcendence ftom witliin tm:} into thi' SifcworU\ Our 
specific concern in the present instance is with the idea of the absolute 
in its positive interpretation^ as expressed by his idea of 'uncondilional- 
ity\ As we also know, Habcrmas now conceives of truth as a Janus faced 
concept that faces in the direction both of lalional discourses and of 
the lifeworld. Whereas discourses remind us of the fiillibilil}' of knowl- 
edge (the negative aspect of the idea of the absolutely the lifeworld 
reassures us of the nfKonditiofiaUt}' of truth {which I have referred to as 



iVfcTCVf CooSf 227 

Its positive aspect}. Wc could also say: it reassures us of tlic cbfectivity - 
of the necessity and uiiivcrsalily - of the tiuc [>ropositions that are the 
pragmatic basis for the behavioural certainties that guide us in our 
everyday practices in the lifcvvorld.^-^ Habermas stresses that action 
rsxjuires us to assume the uncondLtional truth of what wc take to be 
true. ""Wc would step on no bridge, use no car. undergo no operation, 
not even cat an exquisitely prepared meal if wc did not consider the 
knowledge used lo be safeguaa'ded, if we did not hold the assumptions 
employed in the production and execution of our actions to be inje/^^ 
There is Lhus "'a prnirtkul necessity to rely intuitively on what is uncon- 
ditionally held-to-be-true'.*^ He also expresses this as the need for par- 
ticipants in hfeworld action-contexts to he realists: 

BeGLUse acting subjects have to cope with ""the world"" [that is, with a 
world presumed to be objective in the sense of Identical for every- 
one and not at anyone's disposal - MC], they cannot avoid l>eing 
realists iii the context of their lifcworld_ Moreover, they are allowed 
to be realists because ihcii language games and practices^ so long as 
they function in a way that is proof against dlsappointmentH 'prove 
their truth' [sich bewiihren] in being carried on."^* 

Critique of Habtrmas's postinetaphysital 'idea of God' 

However, Habermas^s attempt to salvage a positively constmcd idea of 
the absolute without recourse to metaphysics is not successfiil.^^ His 
idea of 'unconditionality^ appeals to a normative notion of 'coping 
with reality' that relies in turn on what he calls a 'weak' naturalist - 
and ultimately metaphysical - assumption about the progress of 
liistory. In order to see this we inust look more cioscly at his prag'mati- 
cally tooled notion of ' mi conditio iiaiiiy '- 

Habermas argues correctly that everyday action in the lifeworld 
requires us to behave rt.s tfiou^h we arc realLstSn in the sense of pras^nati- 
calty supposm^ the existence of an objective worlds that is^ of a single 
worlds essentiatly identical fot all of us and with some independence of 
our observations. At the sainc time, as he himself acknowledges, the 
fallibilist consciousness that ^ides participants in discourse also reacts 
back upon everyday practices without thereby destroying the dopna- 
tlsm of the lifeworld: 'For actors, who as panicipants in argumentation 
have learned that no conviction is proof against criticismn develop in the 
lifeworld, too^ rather less dogmatic attitudes lowaid their problematizcd 
convictions/^^ Here, too, Habermas is correct. Human agents, when 



228 Phihsnphy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%t Century 

they act as participants In everyday pracUccs in the lifcworld, have to 
presuppose uncondiUonal (ruth for pragmalic reasons; however^ Ihey 

can also be aware rcflcxively of the pragmatic reasons motivating their 
assumplioii- hi other words^ it is not just behavioural certainties that 
have to 'work' in the sense of enabling agents to cope with reality; the 
idea of ^unconditionatily' itself lias to 'work' in the same sense. If it no 
longer enabled human agents to cope with reality^ they would be justi- 
fied in abandoning It. Pul in this way the problem Is clear: in Haber- 
nias's account the positive aspect of the concept of truth has its basis 
in a pragmatic notion of coping with reality This notion is, however, 
neither self-evident nor normatively neutral but rather an evaluative 
standard that itself requires justification- 'Coping with reality" implies 
that there are better and worse ways of relating to reahty. Our concep- 
tlons of what counts as better and worse ways depend In turn on 
evaluative interpretations of human flourishing, which themselves 
depend on some kind of normative - and ultimately metaphysically 
b,iscd - theory of the progress of history. The normative theory on 
which Mabermas relies is a 'weak' naturalist onc- 

The theory is mitnmiht insofar as it relies on the basic assumption 
'that the organic equipment and cultural way of life of homo Si^pleiss 
have a 'natural' origin and are accessible in principle to explanation by 
evolutionary tlieory'.'^^ Its naturalism is 'weak' insofar as it is nonreduc- 
tionist. It docs not rephice conceptual analysis with natural scienHfic 
explanation; nor does it reduce the communicative practices of the life- 
world to, for example, neurologically orblogenetically explicable opera- 
tions of the human brain."^ Habeimas claims that his 'wTak' naturalism 
makes just one fundamental metathcoretical assumption, ft assumes 
that 'our' learning processes - those possible within the framework of 
socio-cultural forms of life - in a certain way merely continue 
antecedent ^evolutionary learning processes' that have in turn given 
rise to the structures of our forms of life»^* 

Mowevern even this 'weak' natjralist account of the progress of history 
relies on a metaphysical assumption. We can see this if we look more 
closely at Malx^rmas's argumeiHj which appears to have the following 
logic. On Habermas's account, natural evolutionary processes are 
'coping' processes - processes of solving problems and dealing with dis- 
appointed expectations - that lead to ever more complex levels of devel- 
opment. Whereas these processes may in fact be purely contingenlj we 
impute to them a cognitive context This supposition is necessary if we 
are to be able to conceive of socio-cultural processes as learning 
processes, hi other words, the attribution of a cognitive content to the 



practices that make possible 'our' soclonziiUural forms of life requires us 
to impjEG a cognitive content to naturEil cvolulionary processes. 

However, as is evidcnL from [he above reconstruction, Habermas's 
argument does not explain why we arc entitled to speak of ^learning^ in 
cither case. Rather^ it relics on the metaphysical assumption that 
htiman bein;^s unavoidably conceive of the progress of history as kiun- 
In^ - as a pnDccss of acquiring knowledge - and not as a cognitively 
irrelevant, purely contingent shift horn one perspective to another It is 
this 'mctaphyslcar assumption that underlies Habermas's 'mctatheo- 
rctlcar assumption of the continuity between socio-cultural and evolu- 
tionary learning processes as a first principle that cannot be disproved. 

[n the end, therefore, llahcrmas Is unable to salvage the positive 
aspect of the idea of absolute - the idea of 'unconditional! ty^ or perfec- 
tion - without recourse to metaphysics- However, as 1 have suggested 
in the first section, this need not be cause for concern. It is not the fact 
that iiormative social theory ulUmatcly relics on metaphysics that is 
problematic but the tendency to deny the effects of history and con- 
tcjtt and the Importance of human free wllL It is not metaphysics that 
normative sociat theorj^ has to guard against but rather the view that 
access to perfect knowledge is available and the view that the progress 
of history towards perfect knowledge and perfect justice is ^mmnteed. 

For our present purposes, this rehabilitation of metaphysics has an 
important consequence. It opens the possibility of debate as to the 
respective merits of the various kinds of metaphysical assumptions that 
unavoidably underlie the Idea of the process of history. For there Is^ of 
course, no need to accept the particular metaphysical assumption on 
which Habermas's theory relics. What is required, rather, are processes 
of unconstrained, hermeneutlcally oriented dialogue with those who 
hold competing views of the progress of historj'. Such dialogues would 
permit discussion of the advantages and limitations of Habermas's 
"w^eak' naturalist position vis a vis other normative accounts of the 
progress of history - including ones that assume the benign guidance 
of a divine will or being. 



Habermas and the validitv of the seinantk contents 

of rtligioii 

There arc also points of convergence and divergence between 
Horkhclmer and Habcrmas with regard to the validity of religious 
Ideas. Both agree that the valldit>^ of the semantic contents of religion 



ZiO Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

is independent of the religious context in which ihcy originated. How- 
evcfH only Habermas concedes the possibilily of religious trulh. 

Habermas and Horkhcimer agree that the value or importance of the 
semantic contents of religion is indcjx^ndent of the origins of these con- 
tents. For example, the validity of moral ideas of human dignity and 
universal solidarity can l>c assessed quite independently of the religious 
framework m which they were initially formulated. More comprehen- 
sively than 1 torkheimcr, who tends to focus on religiDusly based inonil 
ideaSn Hahermas recognizes the religious origins of the key normative 
conceptions guiding the project of a critical theory of society. Ilabcrinas 
acknowledges that normative ideas of fundamental importance to 
modern Western self-under standing (and to a critical theory concerned 
to explore the emancipatory potenhats of thisli such as ethics and 
morality, person and individualitVj freedom and emancipation, cannot 
be grasped without 'appropriating the substance of tiie Judaco-Christian 
understanding of history in terms of salvation'- ^^ He refers to this as a 
''semantic reservoir (of potential meanings')' t^emantisch^a PoU'utml) that 
has to l>e mastered anew by every generation/^-^ At the same time^ how- 
ever, Habermas, like Morkheimcr, distinguishes between the ori^ms of 
ideas - tlieir genealogy - and their iiJipoftdt^ce. Moreover^ like 
Horkheimer - althou-^h for different reasons^ - he holds that rclij^ious 
justifications of moral ideas are not possible: the disenchantment of the 
world that follow^s in the wake of the European Eiillghtenment means 
that morality can no longer look to religion for support for the truth of 
its cliiiins. According to the post -Enlightenment picture, reason is dif- 
fercnliatcd, splil up into various momenta of rationality: for Habermas^ 
the Kantian trio of truth, morality and taste is paradigmatic for this 
differentiation. As a result of the disintegration of reason into its vari- 
ous moments, claims to moral vaMditj^ - like truth and aesthetic valid- 
ity - now constitute a distinct mode of tationality with its own internal 
standards of justification. For this reason, under conditions of moder- 
nit% moral (and other) insights orighially articulated in a religious 
framework must be subjected to a process of critical appropriation and 
transformation if they are to be recuperated within the universe of 
justificatory modes of speech.^-^ This holds not fust for moral ideas but 
for semantic contents in gencraL Habermas refers to the need for 
fy^ethodologknl i]theism in dealing with the semantic contents of reli- 
gion: under conditions of modernity^ neither philosophy nor critical 
fheology^^ can simply appeal to divine revelation for justification of 
religious Ideas but must rather subject thcni to argumentative testing 
in the appropriate types of discourse.^^ 



At limes Hahcrmas has suggested thaE the philosophical task of critical 
approprialion and transformation of the semantic contents of rflLf^ion 
Is now concluded - that the valuable content of religion has been 
translated without remainder into the l>asLC principles of a univcrsalist 
ethics of the type he proposes. ^^ More reccntlyj there is evidence of 
willingness to acknowledge that the task i5 ^Lill ongoing: The process 
of critical appropriation of the essential contents of the religious tradi- 
tion is still in process, its results hard to foresee/'""^ He allow^s thaL j>ost- 
mcLaphysieal philosophy will be able iieithcr to replace nor displace 
religion so long as the language of religion carries with it inspirational 
ofj possibly^ even indispensable semantic contents that cannot - per- 
haps - be fully captured by philosophical language and still await 
translation into justificatory discoursesJ"^ 



Habtrmas'i formal pragmatics ami rtiigioiis truth 

If wc consider niore closelj;' what is at issue here^ we can sec that it is 
the question of reli^ous truth. From the point of view of Habermas's 
tiieory^ semantic contents may be of ditTcrcnt types: they can^ for 
example, be moral, aesthetic, or religious. We may presume that the 
predicate Veligious^ applies when Uic experience from which they 
derive is a religious one; let us further presume that religious experi- 
ences can be described in positive terms, for example^ as the fceHng 
that there is an ultimate purpose to human life that makes It meaning- 
ful. Such experiences cannot as a rule be replaced by arguments: 
no-onc who is unconvinced of the existence of God^ for instancCj is 
hkely to be convinced of it solely through participation in discourse. 
Tleligious conviction seems to rely on an indispensable dimension of 
pefsoiml experience that is a necessary precondition for participation in 
discussion on matters of religious validityj and that provides the 
motivating force for argument. It is for this reason that reiigious truth 
is deemed to lay claim to a kind of validity that is only partially dis- 
cursive. Thus, when Habernias concedes the possibility of specifically 
rchgioijs semantic contents that taiII always in part resist attempts to 
translate them into the language of justificatory discourse, he appears 
to be conceding the possibllitj^ of religious truth. If this Is thp case, it 
would constitute a further important difference between llorkhelmcr 
and Hal>crmas. Although Horkheimer, as we have seen, asserts a con- 
nection between truth and a iiegathrfy construed idea of the absolute^ 
at least in his early writings he argues against a theory of truth that 



232 Pfiih.^ophy ofRi'lii^mr m tto! 21%i Century 

relics on a positiveiy construed idea. His theory thus rules out any posi- 
tive conception of religious truthJ*^* 

in conclusion, I would like to make two points- The first - shorter - 
point is that there is an uninistakabte note of caution in llabcimas^s 
writings as regards the possibility' of non-discursivcl)^ recuperalile 
semantic contentSj and parLicLj]a]]y' so when he refers to religious ones. 
At mostp Halx^mias concedes the possibiilty of specifically religious 
semantic contents that would always resist translation into the language 
of justification: he by no means agrees that such contents exist. ^"^^ 
At best, his posiLion Vhltli regard to the question of religious truth 
seems to be that the jury is still out on whether it should be taken scri- 
ousiy. The second - longer - point is that it is far from clear how the 
notion of religious truth can be accommiCKiated within the framework 
of Habermas's critical theory. 

The challenge posed by religious truth 

Habennas proposes a schema of validity claims Lhat arguably fails to do 
justice to the multiplicity of modes of potentially rational everyday 
language usc-^"-^'^ Tlic question of religious truth higlilights some of the 
difficuItEes of his schema. 

For our present purposes^ the main dif ficuhy with Habermas's theory 
of validity claims is that the c!atms to religious truth raised by religious 
believers do not fct easily into either of the two broad categories identi- 
fied by Habermas- Habermas distinguishes broadly l?ctween validity 
claim? that c^in h^ vindicated in discourse and those that cannot. This 
distinction corresponds to his distinction between universal and non- 
universal validity claims. Discursively redeemable validity claims are 
universal in that they rest on the assumption that, if valid^ everyone 
who participated in a discourse satisf)1ng certain demanding condi- 
tions would have to agree with this judgement.*'-^ It is important to 
HQte here that^ on Habermas's conception, agreement reached between 
participants in discourse is always agreement in a strong sense: partici- 
pants agree to accept a validity claim for the .'^ame reasom}^^^ Non- 
discursivcly rcdcemabic validity claims are non-universal in the sense 
thai ihcy do not rest on this assumption of universal agrcenicnt- 
Habermas sees empirical and theoretical truth claims, on the one hand, 
and claims to moral validity^ on the other, as examples of discursively 
redeemable - universal - validity claims. We will recall that for Haber- 
mas, one aspect of the Janus-faced concept of truth is that w^e deem a 
proposition true if it withstands all attempts to refute it under the 



dein^Lnding condilions of rational argumc illation. The connection 
bcuvccn moral truth and argumcniation is even mote iiiLimatc as 
Habermas asserts an mtenuil link between the two. On his account, Hie 
moral validity of a norm or principle is conceptually tied to a discur- 
sively achieved consensus to ihc effect tliai it is equally in the interests 
of all affected. In the case of question? of moral validity universal agree- 
ment achieved under ideal fustifieatory conditions does not simph- 
iuithorize validity, it sunrantees the Tightness of moral judgefnents. 
In shorty whereas Habcrmas insists on the disjunction between truth 
and justification, he defends a purely cpistemic conception of moral 
truth. Idealized rational acceptability exlmust-i the meaning of moral 
validity. ^*^^ 

By contrast^ claims to aesthetic and to cthicai validity fall into the 
category of n on -discursively redeemable elainis. For Habermas, ethical 
(as opposed to moral] validity claims cannot be vindicated discursively 
because they are always hound to the subjective perspective of a partic- 
ular individual (or col[ectiv[ty>.^°^ Ethical deliberation involves the 
herniencutic clarification of an individuars (oi collectivity's) self- 
understanding and raises chnical questions of a happy or not-failed 
life.^^ Ethical validity claims are thus always context-specific. They are 
not capable of commanding argumentatively achieved universal agree- 
ment hut oniyn at most^ the agreement of a particular group that shares 
a horizon of contingent cultural values."*"^ 

Ilabermas also characterizes aesthetic validitv claims as context- 
specific. Like ethical claims they are held to depend on particulartst 
cultural values and thus not to trajiscend local boundaries- for tiiis 
reason they do not coi^tstitute universal validity claims that can be vin- 
dicated in discourse.^"-* In addition, Habcrmas now emphasizes the 
world'disclosing function of works of art and literature. If I understand 
him correctly, this wo rid- disclosing function sujjgests a further reason 
whv aesthetic validitv claims cannot be vindicated in discouVse fwe 
shali see that the argument here is also relevant in tlie ease of religious 
validity claims). 

In recent years Habcrmas has repeatedly drawn attention to the 
power of works of art fahd literature) to disclose the world in a new 
IV av- Aesthetic claims refer lo semantic contents that cast a new^ light on 
all aspects of reality and that have to he experienced personally as 
wot id-disc Insure before they can be understood. Tlie validity of aes- 
thetic claims thus refers to the work of art's 'sin^larly illuminating 
power to open our eyes to T,vhat is seemingly familiar, to disclose anew 
an apparently familiar reality This validity claim. .-. stands for ^.potential 



2J.4 Pfiihsnphy ofRi'fii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

for ^'truth'' that can be released only in the whole complexity of life- 
cxpcriencc-^^^^ Although Habcfinas has not worked out the details of 
this conception of aesthetic validity, the logic of the argument seems 
clear. 1 take tiis argLinient to run as follows. 

Xf aesthetic validity claims refer primarily to an experience that shows 
us (he world in a new way, potentially changing every a.spcct of our 
everyday life^ th^^ conditions for achie^^ng agreement in discourse 
become even more demanding. In addition to satisfying presuppositions 
governing the conduct of argumentation (such as the requirement that 
only the force of the better argument obtains), participants would have 
to have undergone a similar world-disclosing experience that resulted 
in Mieit seeing the world in a similar (new) w-ay. Furthermore, this 
similar experience would have to be translatable for all affected by it 
into a mutually intelligible discursive language- Otherwise, discursively 
achieved universal agreement on the ^truth' of the work of art would 
be impossible. The difficulties involved in meeling these addiUonal 
conditions make aesthetic claims unsuitable candidates for inclusion in 
the catcKor)' of claims that can be vindicated in discourse. Whereas dis- 
cursively reached universal agreement as to the validity of aesthetic 
claims is not in principle impossible, it would be so difficult to achieve 
that the idea of an idealized rational consensus would be robbed of its 
purpose: it could no longer serve as a criterion - or even guideline - for 
adjudicating aesthetic validity. 

Their unsuitability as objects of a discursively acliieved consensus 
means that aesthetic validity claims cannot, for Habermas, count as uni- 
vcrsal-^^^ j-lowever, he does not appear to see this as cause for concern. 
Indeed, Habermas reinforces the thesis of their non-untvcrsality insofar 
as he seems to confine the svorld -disclosing power of works of art and 
literature to a culture of experts^ maintaining that it requires transla- 
tiDii hy such experts before it can be made accessible for lay persons. 
More precisely^ In the modern world, aesthetic experience is held to be 
the object of the specialized discourses of experts (in this case^ literary 
or art critics} and thus spUt off from everyday life-experience.-^*^ It 
requires niiidiation by literary or art criticism hcfore it can have an 
impact on everyday language and beha\^oiirJ^'* Such criticism ^acconi- 
plls[:Les a process of translation of a unique kind. It draws the experien- 
tial content of the work of art into normal language ..This innovative 
potential then finds expression in the changed composition gf an 
evaluative vocabulary - m the renovation of value-orientations and 
need interpretations - which alters the tincture of modes of life 
through alterinj^ modes of perception/'^^ 



iWcTcv^ Cooke Z^S 

T do not want to pursue the question of Avhcthcr Habermas's character- 
izalion of aesthetic validUy claims is convincing. My inain point in the 
present context is that Habermas explicitly compares and contrasts reli- 
gious validity claims with aesthetic oncs.^^^ On his-admiLtcdly sketchy - 
account, reli^ous claims^ like aesthetic ones, refer to an experience of 
world-disclosure that, as I have shown, creates problems so far as their 
possible vindication in discourse is concerned. Because claims to religious 
validity, like aesthetic claimSn presuppose a personal world-disclosing 
experience as a necessary condition for participation In argumentation^ 
the likelihood (under conditions of modernity) of achieving universal 
agreement in discourse is so remote as to make nonsense of universal 
consensus as a criterion of religious truth - or even as a guideline tor 
ascertaining it However^ although a common reference to world- 
disclosing experience connects religious claims wUh aesthetic ones, 
there are also two important points of difference. 

First of all, by contrast w-ith aesthetic claims (as conceived by 
Habermas}, religfous claims are not the prerogative of experts in a par- 
ticular field of specialization but are raised by ordinary participants in 
everyday practices of speech and action. Habermas acknowledges that 
the claims to religious truth raised by religious believers take place 
within the lifeworld, that is, on the level of everyday communication 
and action. To confine world-disclosing religious experience to the spe- 
cialized discourses of experts fin this case, theologians} would amount 
to a complete neutralization of its experiential content: if its experien- 
tial content is not lo be neutralized, therefore, religion has to assert its 
holistk position in the lifeworld.^'^ 

Secondly^ religious claims^ unlike aesthetic ones^ are not bound to 
the contingent subjective values of individuals or groups but are rather 
universal in aspiration. Habermas explicitly acknowledges the universal 
orientation of theological claims.^ ^^ Admittedly, as a discourse among 
experts^ (criticah theology fulfils the Habcrmasian requirement that 
truth claims be formulated In the specialized language of discursive jus- 
tification. But, as Habermas clearly recognizes^ theological discourses, 
If they are to be distinguishable from philosophical discourseSj have to 
take seriously tlie claims to truth raised by religious believers. Tf theology 
were to adopt the 'methodoiDgical atheism"" appropriate for philosophy 
In dealing with religious semantic contents, it would undermine the 
entire theological enterprise. For this reason^ at least sonic of the truth 
claims raised by theology merely articulate at a higher level the claims 
to truth raised by religious believers in their everyday lives. In other 
words, the theological claims that articulate religious validity claims 



236 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'fii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

are structurally similar to them. Tlicrcforc, what holds for theological 
vaUdlty claims must also hold for rehgious claims: ihcii claim to valid- 
ity Is not restricted a priori to the experiential basis of a particular culture 
or context but transcends all purely local boundaries. This crcales 
problems for Habermas's theory^ however, for truth on his view must 
be capable of being vindicated in discoursed ^^ Religious experiences 
would thus have to be translatable inlo the language of scientific 
discourse - and, as we have seenn there arc serious difficulties here. 
From the point of view of Habermas^s theory of validity claims, the 
main problem is the following: The claims of religious believers (which 
form the basis for many theological claims} cannot be ^nndicated in dis- 
course and are thus non-universal. Tor this reason they cannot be com- 
pared with claims to theoretical or empirical truths or with claims to 
moral validit>'^ At the same time, as he acknowledges, they are neither the 
prerogative of a specialized culture nor are they bound to particularist 
and contingent cultural values. For this reason Lhey cannot be com- 
pared with claims to ethical and to aesthetic validity- Habermas is thus 
left in the position of apparently recognizing the holistic and universal 
tlirust of rehgious validity claims while denj^ng them their entitiement 
to the predicate 'truth'. 

As I see it, there are two paths open to Habermas here. One possibility 
is to ieavc his schema of validity claims as it is and find some way - 
however awkward - of subsuming religious validity into one or other 
of his two broad categories. The second possibility^ which 1 favour^ is a 
fundamental reconsideration of his theory of validity. Although I have 
not been able to show this in the present context, 1 think there arc 
serious piobknis, in particular^ with his accounts of ethical and of 
aesthetic validity One problem here is his tendency to reduce the 
notion of ^experience' to empirical experience based on observation or 
controlled scientific experiment. Only experience of this i^ind is admit- 
ted by Habermas as evidence for argument in spcciahzed discourses 
concerned wUh truth claims. In his recent ivritin^s^ however, he seems 
to hold a broader view of the kind of e\adcnce that may count as a reason 
in discursive processes of justification- In the case of moral discourse^ for 
example, he now acknowledges that moral feelings count as relevant 
reasons. ^^^-^ This suggests that ethical, acsthetiCH and religious feelings 
and experiences might also count as evidence when participants in dis- 
courses argue on disputed matters of validity. Admittedly, the question 
of how such evidence can be processed is a difficult one. For, against 
Horkheimer, it can be argued that the mere psesence of a feeling or 
assertion of an experience is not sufficient: we need to find a vantage 
point that would permit a criiical perspective on subjective feelings 



iWiicv^ Cooke 237 

and<?xpericnccs.^^^ Nonetheless, if Habcrmas's theory is to do justice to 

clhlcalj acslhctiQ and religious trulli [\ must penetrate deeper into the 
relationship between argument and the varieties of human experience. 



Notts 

1* Mjtlnas Lutz-Eachniiinn offers a good overview of the develofka^iit of 
Horkht^imtr's thinking with respect to leligioEii. dia^ving attenEion both to 
the line of continuity between the early and la(er Horkheimei and the 
pessimistk turn that characterizes his philosophy In the later period. Si't 
M. Lutz-Bachm^nn, ""HiiiTaanEtat und KuLiglon. Zu Max Horkhtiniers DeuCung 
de::> ChristentLims', in A. Schmidt und N. Aitwicker {eds^ Mra Horklmfuer 
ht'ute:^ WeFi: itud Wirkimg, Frankfurt am Main, 19S6 and M_ Lutz-Bachmann^ 
'ETkenntniskritik unJ Cottej;idee im Spawerk Max Horkheimerf^', in M_ L.utz- 
Bachmann Cedj^ Kritische TUt^arit wkI Keii^km, WiJrzburgr 1^7. 5ff aha 
J_ Jiabennas^ "Max Horkheimer: Zur EntwkkJungsgeschichte s&ines Werfcs' in 
his Texts ami KoiJtexte, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp^ 1991_ 

2. A^ far as f can see^ thi^ general Elic?firv', as cnnceived by HorkheimeT^ has a 
diagnostic component and a nonnLitlve one. Its diagnostic component 
requires of ll interdiiciplinaFy rescardi methods: in order to ascertS:in correctly 
the causes of social evils it must enter into a relationship of cooperation with 
the social sciences (cf, M_ Horkheimer. 'Critical Theory and Traditional 
Theorj^, ui his Critii-ni Thi'or}'^ trans, by M. CCcnnellr New York: tj:>n tinuum, 
1972^, p. 233^). Its normative component requires of it an account of human 
interests and desSTes^ as these have been articulated historically in social 
struggles [:s^i' note 51 belowj^ and an acc1:^unt of the social stmcEures most 
appropriate for satisfy'ing these. Particularly in the case of the latter, critical 
theory draws on the methods and findings of various social sciences^ for 
eKamplCr on those of political economy i^tre. for example^ M. Horkheimer^ 
'Materialism and Metaphysics"", in Cnticai T/]fory, pp_ 42-6i_ 

3. Horkheimer insists Eliat mattrialisT theory is primarily a theor>" of transforma- 
tory praxis. He criticizes the frequent misinterpretation of it as a response to 
metaphysical questions ^foi example^ as an attempt to explain the 'enigma of 
beEng'^_ It is then reduced to the simpSe claim that only matter and its move- 
ments are real. Against thES^ Horkheimer stresses ttiat materialism is defined 
principally in tenns of the ft;5jts it sets itseif, specifically the overcoming of 
human suffering and oppression. (See his 'Materialism and Metaphysics'^ 
pp- 10^2 L> 

4. HorkheiBTier accuses Hegel of maintaining the pcsssLbility of a perfect reconcil- 
iation bet^veen concept and object^ and hence of concluding the dialectical 
process of thought or history \see, for example, M. Horkheimer, 'Ptoblem 
der Wahrheit'^ in his Kr?tL'H*:he Tfieane^ voL 1, edited by A. Schmidt. Frankfurt 
am Main: E"iischer U96S>; M_ Horkheimer and T. \V_ Adorno^ Diat^tic of 
Enii^hit'mnent, trans, by John Gumming, New 7orfc: Continuum^ 197Z. p. 24. 
I leave open the question of whether his interpretation of Hegel is coirect_ 

5- Horkheimer, 'Problem der Wahrheit; pp. 242-3. 



238 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

6. Horkheimer is criticat of Kantian foimalism, claiminj^ that the emptiness oi 
its conception of moraUEy is one reason why people seek to escape from it 
to more substantial religious views ^ct. Tmblem der Wahrlieit'^ pp. 236t.)_ 

7- Horkheimer^ 'Materialism and Metaphysics'^ pp- 45-6; M_ Horkheimer^ 
'Matenalismus und MoraS\ in Kntische Tti^orie, voL 1, pp. lOS-9- 

B. Horklieimer, 'MaEertalismus und Moral", p. 97ff. 

9. Ibid, p- KKh 

LO. M_ Horkhfiimer, 'E£?merkungen zur philosophischen Anthropologie"^ in 
Kxitiache Tlitrone^ voL 1. p- 2L0 (cf. also 'Mateiialism and Melaphy^iics'^ p, 44>- 

11. Horkheimer, 'Bemerkuni^n zur philosophlschen AnthrcpoEogie'r p. ZOH_ 

12. Horkheimer does sugg^est that this incentive is felt particulaily stFongly by 
the social cla=LS tJiat suffers moit from the capitalist system - which in the 
19305 he held lo be the proletariat {d. 'Materia lismus und Vloral'^ p. I04)j 
nonetheless^ he does not restrict the desire for a better order of things to 
this social clasfi. 

13. Horkheimer^ 'Materiallsnius und Moral, p. 94ff_ 

14. Horkheimei offers such an explanation in 'Bemerkungen zur philo&ophischen 
Anthropologic', p. 213_ 

15. Horkheimer suggests that the prEnc3p]€ of free and e-i^ua] economic 
e_xchange leads to an idea of human beings as beings without a name or a 
place or a specific destin)^ an idea that is essential to the modern conception 
at God: see his 'Zu Theodor Haeckers "Der Christ und die Geschichte'""r i" 
Khtischi; TheonL\ voL 1^ p. 371. 

16. Horkheimer, Tioblem der Wahrheit'. p. 234_ 

L7. Horkhcimei^ 'Problem der Wahrheit^ P- 245; 'Materialism and Metaphysics'^ 

P llff' 

L8_ Cf. Horkheimer^ 'Probtem der Wahrheit''^ pp_ 25S^?; 'Materialismus und 

Moral', pp- lC)B-9. 

19. Horkheimer^ 'Materialism and Metaphysics', p_ 26_ 

20. Horkheimer, 'Zu Theodor Haeckers "Der Chr[st und die GeschkhEe^"^ 

pp 370-1 

21. M_ Horkheinierr 'Ejoismus und Freiheitsbewegung', in KntiscSie Tiieorie, 
voL 2^ edited by A. 3chniidtr Frankfurt am Main: Fischer^ 1968^ p. St)_ 

22. Horkheimer, 'Egoismus und Treiheitsbewej^ng', p. 47. The phrase used by 
Horkheimer here is 'AtheisE aus inteilektueller BeLturtni5losigkeit\ 

23. Horkheimer, 'Zu Theodor Haeckers "Der Christ und die Geschichte"^ 
pp. 36S-6_ 

24- Horklieimer, 'Kemerkunj^en zur philosophlschen i\,nthrcpo[ogif''r P- 207. 
ZS, Horkheimer, 'Materialism and Metaphysics'^ p_ 27; ''BemerkQ]igen zur 
philosophischen AnChropologie', p. ZIK 

26. Horkheimer, 'Materialasm and Metaphysics', p_ 44_ 

27. Horkheimer, 'Materialism and Metaphysics'^ p- 45; 'Eemerkungon zur 
phtlosophiscJien AnthropoJogie', p, 21 1; 'MatcrSaEismus undTvloial'^ p- lOfi. 

2S. Horklieimer^ 'Materialismus und Morale p. 93, 

29- Horklieimer and Adorno, Dialectic of Ejiiif^itcnrj^re^it P- 54. 

30- Horkheimer, ' Material] smus und Moral', p. 93, 

31. HorkheimeFj 'l^oblem der WalirJiuif, pp. 275-6; cf. also 'Zu Theodor Etaeckers 
"Der Christ und die Geschichte", p. 366. 

32. Horkheimer, 'Zu Theodor Haeckers "Der Christ and die Geschichte'^'j p. 366_ 



Mtiew Cookt^ 2J!9 



33. M. Horkheimer^ 'Gedanke zur RelEgion', In Kriti.^ihe Thr^oiie, vol. 1^ p. 373, 

34. M. HorEvheimerr Theism and Atheism^, in his Critiijue of IfLWitmeiitut Reti.'iOfj, 
trans- by M_ O'ConneSJ and others^ Kew York: C2ontinuum, 1974^ p_ 47. 

35. Cf_ Horkheimer, "Materaaiismus unJ Moial^, p_ 93- 
^6. Horkheimei. 'Gedanke zut Religion^ p. 374- 

37- Horkheimer, 'Zu Theodor Haeckers "Der Christ und die Gea:hachte'-"\ p. 37Z 
3S, HoTkheimei, 'Gedaaike zur lltligion'^ p. 37S. 

39- Ibid- 

40- IbSd- For a brief di^cu^^lon of Bea^janiln's Jiotion of anamnetk soladarit)'^ see 
J- Habermas, 'A Reply to my Critics"^ in J-B. Thompson and D. Head (eds)^ 
Habenmu: Cntii-al D^l:hil(^.\ Cambradge, MA: M[T Presi, I9S1. j^p. 246-7. 

41 _ HoTkheimer, 'Zu Theodor Haeckers"Der Christ und die Geschichte"', p_ j?72. 
42_ Horkheimef. 'Gedanke zut ReHgaon'r pp- 375-6. 

43- Hoikheinser, Theism and Atheism'r pp^ 47ff- 

44- Hoikheimer, Trobleni der Wah^heit^ p. 247. 

45- The German term '^kb bcmihre^i' may be translated as 'corroboration' or 
'proving to be true', in the sense of turning out to be tnie^ standing the test^ 
withstanding critical s^crutany [note its connection with wahr. tme)- "Where 
confuivion is likeJv I use the German term. 

46- Horkheimer, Troblem der Wahrheit^ pp. Z49ff- 
47. Ibid-, pp 249-50. 

4H. !bad-, p- 245. 
49. Ibid-, p- 246. 

50- Ibid-, p-254. 

51- Ibid-j PP- 25 Iff- It could be argued that in taking its orientation from histor- 
ically articulated interests and de:vares Horkheimer^s own theory is open to 
the chaige he levels against pragmatism Uliat is^ of boundless confidence in 
the world as at actually exists). In my view Horkheamer avoids this accusa- 
tion insofar as he insists on a discrepancy betLveen human interests and 
desires and Ehear satasfaction under given social conditions. Social struggles 
are practical teitimony to the gap between aspiration and actualization; the 
method of determinate negation is the theoretical tool designed to expose 
it- To be suiCr the possibihrv- of this gap rests on certain - possibly con- 
tentious - normative^ natursJE^t presuppositions about the moral validity ol 
desires and teelings- 

52. Horkheimer, Troblem der Wahrheit', p. Z52. 

53. Ibid-, p- 253. 

54- Horkheimer and Adorno, Dkdcctic *ff Et^iighwsmait, p. 24. 

55- Set' notes 2 and 51 above- 

56u Horkheimer and Adorno, Diafeclic ^f Enii^i^tstt^nmeiil:, pp- 23ff. 
57. Hahermas, Tf.Yff umi Kontexte, pp- llO^f. 
SS- Ibid-, pp 105-6- 

59. Ibid-, p- 119. 

60. Ibid-, p- 125. 

61. Habermas emphasizes the influence on Horkheimer of Schopenhauer's thesis 
ot the unity of ail forms of life {see Texte umi Idmtexte, p. I20j. Although he 
does not draw this conclusion explicitly, one could say that in the modern 
world the function of the idea of God as co^rwkitiof! Ls connected not just 
with its abiliU' to project a reconciliation beriveen the individual and the 



240 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

collectivity but also islth its abiJity to effect a unity between the disparate 

a5.pecE5 of an individual human life. 

62. Habeimas^ Texte mid Koiitext^F. pj"). lQS-6. 
6:i. Ibid.^ p. 97. 

64. Ibid., p- K)3. 

65. i"ff J. Habcirmss. The Tkmry of Comnmni^ative Action, vol. 1^ tran:v_ by 
T McCarthy, Cambritlge, MA: MIT Press, 19B4, pp. 'S77tL 

66. HabtrmaSj 'A RepEy to my Critics'^ p_ 232. 

57. J_ Habermas, Kriowiedf^c and Hmnan J>itfrejts, tran5. by J_ Shapiro, Londnn: 

Heinemannr 1972_ 
6S_ J, HaL>ermas, 'What is Universal Prjigmatics?' in M, CcK>ke (eti.), Hubernhis: 

On the Prti^mtitici of Cmiimunifrtitiaii^ Cambridge, MAr MIT Pres^, 1^9f4, 

pp- 21-104. 

69. Habermas, Tcxte uml Kotftextt'. pp. 1 19-2()_ 

70. The tatJe of Habermas'i essay in his Ti^xlt wnl Kimtexti' is; 'Transzendenz von 
innen, Transzendenz ins diesseks'. An approximate translation is: Tran- 
scendence from within, transcendence into this world'. 

71 . It also makes a daffercnce at which ^e^'ei the idea of God enters the theorv Else- 
where I have arjued thac normative social theory requires a r^vo-step juiEifica- 
tory strategy. In addicton to a mode of justification LJidi appeals to normative 
standards, immanentto a given cukural and socjal context, it must aSso justify 
these fundamental normative standards through reference to a normative 
account of the progress of history I contend. furtiienT^ore^ that a normative 
account of the progress of history ultimaiely cannot avoid reMng on a meta- 
physical assumption, be this a naturalistj rationalist or religious one. At this 
le\'e], the metapliysicat assumption of a divine wilt or a divine being competes^ 
for eKampie, with a metaphysical assumption of the necessary evolution of tlie 
species. St^e M. Cooke, 'Bet^veen "Contextuallsm" and "Objectivism": the 
Nonnatlve Toundations of Social rhilosophy"^ Criticut Honzosi^k, I, 2 *2(K)0|i_ 

72. In my \ieiv. there is a line of continuity mnning through Hcrkheimer's 
writings that enabtes us to interpret e%^en the later Horkheimer'5 notion of 
absolute meaning in a purely negative way: as signifying the impossibility 
of closure. However^ since this issue is likely to be of interest mainly to 
scholars of Horkheimer, E do not wisli to pursue it further ]iere. 

7^. Habermas stresses this atfinity between his theory and Horkheimer^s when 
he writes: Tor Horkiieimer " mater ialism'"^ always also had the connotation 
of being criticat of philosophy: It stood for fN}.^ti}ietaphysiail thinking/ {Texte 
liiui KtvUi^xtt, p. 92t- 

74. Both Horkheimer and Habermas share an emphasis on the need for an 
inteidiscipiinary approach to a critical theory of society {iftr, for example, 
Horkheimer^ 'Traditional and Critical T^ieory'^ p^ 23!^; J. Habermas^ Tliiloso- 
phy as Stand-in and Interpreter' in his I\^iorai Ca^iSL-iou.'inc.'is ami Co/uimmica' 
ttve Ai'twn, trans, by C_ Lenhardi and S. Weber Nichoisen, Cambridgej MA: 
MIT Press, 1990, pp. 1-20). 

75. See Habermas, 'What is Universal Pragmatics?' For a discussion of Habermas's 

■ BnguEstic grounding of critical theory st^e my Language ami Ri^astjiU! a ^n^ciy 
of HateriHa^y's fanu^fl I'*ragi}iittics. Cambridge^ M.\: MIT Press, 1994, 

76. J_ Habemias, 'Wahrheitstheorlen', reprinted in his Vbrstcitfit^j imd Er^anzimj^en 
zjrr TheGiie des koi7Ji!iiinikatiyeii Handeins'. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp^ 1984_ 



Mcrevf Cookf 241 

77_ The relevant essays can be fGund m J_ HabermaSr IVfEft^/jfaY umi Rechtferti^i^ag, 
Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp^ 1999. One of these, "'Rkharti Rorty's Prag* 
matlc Turn', is tran slated in Cooke ied_), Htiben^ma: ou t!ii3 Pr^i^fmttics of 

Cofuimms cation, pp. 343-E52. 

7a_ This Is not a new deparEure. AJlhough Habermaa in his earlier ^vritmgs 
defended i\ basicaHy episfi^mk view of truth ai idealized rational acceptabil- 
ity, he was uiualiy also concurneJ to emphae^aze the difference between 
truth and JQF;tificatio]i by dramn^ atlention to the unconditional charactei 
we attribute to truth- However, up to recently it was quite unclear what 
kind of poscnnetaphysical basas could be found for our understanding oE 
truth as a property that cannot be lost. 

79. See note 77 above, 

SO. From the early 19KOs onwards^ Habermas appeared to hold a view of truth as 
JdeaEi^d rationa] acceptability^ According to this position, a proposition is 
tme ifit could be iustified under the conditions of the ideal speech situation. 
Truth is a rej^Jl^tive idea, the anticipation of an infinite rational consensus. 
In his more recent writings {see note 77 abo^-ej^ however^ Habermas 
acknovi^iedges convincing objections to this conception. 

ai_ There is r^o evidence that Habermas iiimself disttnguiSihes between these 
two aspects. It should be noted^ therefore^ that both the distinction 
beiween. and description of the two aspects as a 'negative' and a 'positive 
on^'r respectively^ is based on }uy reading of his work. 

HZ_ Habernias^ Wahrtreit umi Ri^cktfi^ftigii^iSj pp. 31^ 247; Habermas^ 'Rorty's Trag- 
matic Turn'r p :p5S. 

83. Cf- Habermas^ Wi:ihriieit. imd Rechtfertigitng, p. 293. 

B4_ Habermas, 'Rorty's Pragmatic Turn', p. 364; cf. Habermas^ WaM}^it und 

Rt^ciiifi^rti^mi^. p. 253- 
85. tiabermaSj 'Rojty's PragmatEC Turn'r p. ii72. 

S6_ Ibid-, p. :J7(>; si?e aiio Hatermias, Wtihrheil und Rechtfirtigimg pp. iZ-S^ 

291-3. 
87. The same can l>e ^aiJ of his proposed postmetaphysical interpretation of 

the ^legtitive aspect of the idea of the absolute^ as expressed by the notion of 

fa!hbihty_ Howervet^ I cannot pursue this matter here. 

+ 

S3L Habermas^ "Rorty's Pragmatic larn'r p. .^7] . 

H9_ Hal>ermas, W^ilsrfa^it and R^chtf'^nipmg, p_ 38_ 

90 Ibid 

91. Ibid-, p- 37- 

92- J- Habernsas, PostfuetaphyTiictil Tf\iHkii\i^, irans- by W.M_ Hohengartenj 

Cambridge, MA: Mil" Press, L992, p. 15. 
93. Ibid-, p- 15- 

94- "We have seen that Hortheimer holds that justification of moral beliefs is 
neither necessary nor pos:>ibte. Instead he appeals Eo historically articulated 
feelings, for example, ot sohdarity or of desire for happiness- 5qcIi feelings 
are 'natural facts' requiring no justification. 

95- Habermas, Tfxti^ imd Kontextc, pp- 13S-&- 

96- Ibid-, p- ]^^J^. This is theology^'s dilemma; .?£^ esp. pp. 1.^7ff. 

97- Ibid-, pp 129 and J:^6- 

9B- J- Habermas, Die ^leuf Unubeisiiiuiii-hki.% Frankfurt: 5uhrkamp, 19^5, p- 52- 
99. Habermas, Tcxte und Kontexte, p. 141. 



242 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

LOO. Ibid,^ pp. 141f. Originally in P^ysttJieti^phy^iciil Tliinkui^, p_ 5L 

lOL v\Fguably, Horkheimer's theory has no room caiia'p^tdity for a nDtion of 
specBfi-caliy retigious truth insofar as it tails to recognize jnodiEmiEy's. ditferen- 
tiation of substantive reason into varionjij fomuJLy conceived^ dimensions of 
vahdity. If Vk^ accept the basic premise of Habennas's vie^v^ whkh is that reli- 
gious tnjth 3ays claim to validity that is of a different kind fromj for example, 
thevalidicy ctaims raised bj' physics, historv", the Law or literature, it as -easy to 
agree that Horkheimer's conception of truth is too undiffeiti:ntiatfid to aJlow 
fof significant differences in modes of justification, Admiltediy^ acceptance 
of Habemias-'s thesis regarding the modern differentiation of reason raises 
complex issues about the relationship between the moments oi rationaEity; 
in particular, it raises the question of whether these moments can L>e rein* 
tegrated without recourse to metaphysics, 

+ 

102. When conceding the possibility oJ' jelagious semantic contents that cannot 
be retrieved discursively. Habermas tends to suggest that the existence of 
such semantic contents is doubtful ae^, for example^ Pa^Uhi'taphyniofi 
Tiiinking. p_ 51^ where he refers to a lellgious semantic content that 'eludes 
{for the time hei^j^?\ the explanatory force of philosophical language and 
continues to resist translaiicn into reasoniiig discourses". ILmphasis added.] 
A rare example ot engagement with the question of rehgious truth can be 
found in his reply to some critics at a theotogica! conference held in i98B 
at the University- of Chicago {s^ Texte iimt Kontexte^ pp. 127-56). Here^ 
Habermas argues that theology tias to take seriously the validity claims of 
religion - and criticizes some theologians for failing to do so. At ihe same 
time^ he acknowledges the difficulties connected with any such attempt - 
without^ however, indicating any solution. 

Wii, See my L<uigii{tge ami R^asiin, ch. 3. My discussion in the following draws 
on the argument in this chapter. 

104, Such condEtions include^ for example, the necessary presuppositions that 
only the force of the better argument prevails, or that everyone concerned 
is entitled to participate on an equal basis. 

105, Cooke (ed.)p Hubenuas: oh the Pnigmatics DfCo^uiuiiitiSiatit?ii^ pp_ 320-1. 

106. KabeimaSj Wtihriieit und Rt^chtferti^iHg. p. 297. 

107. Habermas, Tt'xte wkS Koi^ttrxte. p. 149_ 

lOS- J. Hal>ermas, } notification und Appifcatio}!, trans, by C Cronin, CambS^ge^ 

MA: MIT Press, 1993, pp. 1-17_ 
L09_ [n 'Realizing the Post-Conventional Self [Philosophy anti !i-(H'iat Critici^m^ 
vol. 20, no- 1/2 (1994^ pp. 67-101). [ argue that HahenHas's account of eth- 
ical va] id Et}*^ claims is unsatisfactory in that it tails to distinguish ad^iquately 
bet^veeai two senses in which validity c3aims can be context-specific. 
Cf. also my 'Are Etiiical Conflicts Irreconcilable?" in Ptiiloii^>phy and Socini 
Cnticisf}f, vol- 2J5, no- 2 ^ 1997:i, pp. l-19j- 
110. Habermas, Tii^uiy ^f Commwucatsv^ Ai'tion, Yol. 1^ p- 42- 
Ll 1. Cooke (ed.), Habenmi.'i' on ^le Pnj;puatics GfCofurminia^tion, p, 415, Habermas 
here cites Albrecht Wellmer's essay. Truths SemhEance, Reconciliation', in 
his The Per.'iistence of h-ioiiennty, trans, by D. Midgely, Cambridge^ MAi MIT 
Press, 1991. 

112, ClearJy^ this contrasts with Kanf^s position on the universality of aesthetic 
judgements in his Cntiijiie of Jiid;^]ei!t, trans- by W-S. Pluhar, Indianapolis: 
Hackett rubEishingCo-, 1987- 



Lt3. HaberniaSj Texte umi Kotitexte, pp_ 146fl_ 

LI4. Cxyoke (edj, HifhL'niins: on :he Prci^iinmtics ofCos^whink'atiois, pp. 396^f_ 
lis. rbid-, p- :i97- 

116. Habermaij Ti^xte wni Kiyntext*;, pp_ 146-7. 

117. Ibid., p_ 147. Of course the same can be said of aesthetic experience. 
Indeed, Wellmer- whomHjbt^rmas cites appmvingty in this legard - seems 
to be emphasizing precisely the liolistlc aspect of aesthetic experience [set 
Wellmer^ TVuth. Semblance^ ReconciJJation'). 

LIS. Hjbermas {YVjrfe iirui K^fiti^jcttfj p. 140J acknowledges thai tlias must t>e true 
for theological cEaims tjun valicliEy claims. It must therefore also ho3d i^or 
religious claims qua validity cEaims. 

119. rbid_, p_ 1^7_ 

12(>. Habcrmas^ Wahrhcit xmd Rcchtfcrti^m^^ pp. Z77-&. 

IZL 5f4/ Cooke^ 'Between "ConteAtuaiism"* and ■'Objectivism"^: the Normative 
Toundations of Social Philosophy'. 



15 

Voices in Discussion 

D.Z. Phillips 



H: I have endeavoured (q expound critical theory through the 
developments in the work of Horkhcimer He gave this title to his the- 
ory to distinguish it from orthodox Marxism. Mis v^'orlc went through 
three phases. His work dufiiig llic first pha^e can be compared to that 
of Fcuerbach and Mar.x- Once wc have thrown off its religious s^ise^ 
the essence of reltj^on can be seen as the struj^gle for a better world. He 
did not agree with tlic Leninist view tliat telipon was an oppressive 
institution- Instead, he emphasized llie finitude of life, and thought 
ihat religion saves us from a Lhou^hUcss oplamisni. In this lie was 
influenced by the pessimism of Schopenhauer 

In his second phase, Horkhcimer cooperated with Adorno in a critique 
of the Enlightenment, by emphasizing the negative aspects of Judaism. 
The ne^atioii of optimism is not Leased any longer on a conception of 
absolute reasoning. 

In his Lhird phase, influenced by Kant, Morkheimer is far more scep- 
tical He said that ^the tiling in itself is unknowable. He did not trust 
liuman language or cognition- I-iis notioii of 'the unconditioned' must 
be thought of in a regulative, Kantian sense. As in Kant's First Critique 
it is not an actuai reality^ but a necessary feature of human reasoning. 
For the late Horkhcimer the religious and the philosophical concept of 
God is onc^ via the notion of justice. The hope is for a better world- 

O: iL is essential Lo recognize tliat critical iheor)'' is a practically oriented 
philosophy, rather than a speculative thcor>^ On the one hand, 
Horkhcimer Lhoughl tliat teltf^ion is a regressive force if people arc dep- 
endent on it. The better order he longed for was to be shaped by people"^ 
actual interests- Tliis is tlic only way to overcome oppression. On the 
other liand, religion can liave real dignity if it comes out from 



244 



DZ. rtiiHip^ 245 



the niidsl of this oppression and furthers progressive interests. B\3t 

Horkheiiner thought that this link was contingent^ stnce^ like all ideahst 
philosophies, religious concepts can mean anyihing. So religion is 
replaceable- The better order does not need an appeal to the absolute- 
It may liavc an important rote at a certain time in histoiy^ but^ again^ 
this is contingent. Furlhcrniore, its promise of salvation is an illusion 
aiid turns us away from llie practical problems that need to be 
addressed. We need to be released from the doctrinal and institutional 
aspects of reiigion. Idealists and materialists alike need to recognize 
that an appeal to the absolute cannot be maintained- At Jast^ 
Horkhcimer sees the value of religion as a call for ne\^er-ending change^ 
but he is ambivalent towaids It since its value will always depend on 
circumstances- 

Habennas thought that Horkhcimer was more positive towards jcli- 
gion He accuses him of utopianism and of turning away from the 
impcrtant issues. Ilabcrtnas docs not think that social action needs 
philosophical justification. Despite a common aim their purposes differ, 
but 1 shaEl concentrate on what Ilabermas says about their convergence. 

Habermas has an idea of truth which is pragmatic and yet absolute 
in that it calis one beyond the present situation. No closure is possil"?ie. 
But this role is not rch^ous. He is also interested in the semantic 
content of reHfrion, and argues that its moral ideas are independent of 
their religious form. Reason ts differentiated In different modes of 
reasoning. Therefore, we need a nieliiodologLcal atheism to deal with reli- 
gion. Habermas thought that this critique has been concluded and that 
the hope lies in a universal human ethics. Lately, however, Habermas has 
changed his mind and said that this critique has not been fulfilled and 
that it may not lie possible lo capture religious truths in some philo- 
sophical form equivalent to them. 

Can Habermas accommodate religious truth? The tfiSftculty lies in 
his theory of validated claims. He argued that while empirical and 
moral claims can be vindicated in discourse, this cannot be said of 
aesthetic and rehgious claims. 

Habermas said that ccriain aesthetic and ethical claims are specific in 
content, b^ing dependent on cultural values- Sut he also recognized that 
art and literature can open up new worlds, but must l?c experienced to 
be understood- The conditions for vindication here are impossibly hij^h, 
since all people would have to sec the world in the same way. So it is in 
religion - it offers a world-view- But there are important differences. 
There are no experts in reli;;;aon as there arc in aesthetics. It concerns 
the everyday world. The trouble with philosophical arguments is that 



246 Pfiihsnphy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

thc}^ negate the existential import of religion. The value of religion is 
not confined to the individual, but is universal in its aspiration. 

Yet, there is a prnblem, sIiicGh obviously, llieology caniiol adopt 
methodological atheism. How is religious truth to be vindicated in dis- 
course? As far as I can see there arc only two possible ways ahead for 
Habf rmas in this respect. Mrsl, he can retain his criteria of vindication 
and try to subsume religion under them. Second, he should revise his 
criteria of vindication and make them more flexible to accommodate 
different modes of thought. 1 hope this second course will be adopted. 

D: You have presented two ways of assessing rehgi^^ One is to ask 
whether religious claims are tiue. The second is to ask whellicjr thcie 
claims can be translated without remainder Into mora! or political 
terms. Obviously, the latter alternative will conimEnd itsdf more to 
tliosc who aic non-religious. 

H: 1 do not think one begins with religious experience. Oitc must have 
the requisite concepts to have the experience. All %ve mean by method- 
ological atheism is a methodological approach to these concepts^ so 
you could say that you find it in Aquinas, liut^ of course^ Habcrmas is 
discussing it in the context of post- metaphysical philosophy. 

C; I have a question and a puzzle wliich I want to address to H and 0. 
My question is whether Habcrmas has now gone further and said that 
in the cultural conversation rcli^ous meanings have to be recognized 
as suigeixeris and cannot be analysed away in other terms. 

My puzzle concerns the use of 'methodological atheism"". 1 can see 
that it meant to deliver the enquiry from the framework of religious 
idealism. But If the aim is to do justice to different modes of thought, 
why is atheism privileged in ttiat way? It should be one mode of 
thought among others. The aim would be to do justice to the world in 
all its variety. Once again, I thought of Wittgenstein's '111 teach you 
differences/ Instead of ^nethodotogical atheism/ why not speak of 
disinterested enquiry or neutral enquiry? 

H: I accept entirely what you say about 'methodological atheism . It is 
an unfortunate term for the reasons you give and should be dropped. 

As to your first question, again you are right. ?Tabermas now recognizes 
that icligious content is sui ^aitris, 

O: The only thing I'd add to Hahermas's recognition of the distinctive 
character of religious mcaniiigSj is the qualification that he'd wisli it 

was not true. 



DZ. niiilip^ 247 



G: You spoke of Ihe 'world-transforming' experiences of aesthetics and 

rciigion. You also said tliat relij^ion does not depend on experts as aes- 
thetics does, and lliat lis claims are more universal. 

Now, what it that 'world-transforming' experience of a religious kind 
happened to a philosopher? Wouldn't that mean that he would see all 
things, induding philosophy, rcli^ously? But your method or, at least, 
that of Habermas, insists that philosophy must be pluraltst So what is 

beiiig advocated is a philosophy for the non-'religLous. 

. - - #. 

O: The experience you talk of would have extensive implications which 
could not be contained in Halx^nnas's system. One could not maintain 
methodolo-^ical athctsm. Of course, in the end, everything depends on 
one's philosophy. 

B: But Is it simply a ffce-for-all as far as which philosophies are or are 
not included? 

H: For Horkheimer there was a criterion by which philosophy is to he 
assessed^ namely, whether it furthered sympathy (or the oppressed. 
Furthering the moral law^ gives the opportunity for political action. But 
there is a problem once you recognize, as Habermas did, that there are 
different conceptions of justice. 

M: It is difficuh to get people to aim for an ideal when they are victims 
of oppression. The issue is how the claims of the innocent are to be 
heard. 

O: Horkheimer recognized that^ hence his denial that there can he 
closure on the call for justice. He hccomcs worried that any consensus 
reached will, in fact, fail to fceognize the sufferings of some minorily. 
Habermas recognizes this criticism, but chooses to disregard it. 

H: Horkheimer Is, in some ways, more realistic than Ilabetmas- The 
latter hopes that the universal embraces everyone. He has a transcen- 
dental notion of consensus. It is a formal idea that is a precondition tor 
any moral dispute. It is not that we know the goal and arc w^orklng 
towards it^ but it denies closure to the moral q^ucst. 

/: You say that it is not a theory of justice, but that it Is normative 
nevertheless. I do not thlnlv that will be 'cooF enough for C 

O: ll^bermas's view is based on his notion of the nocinativity of lan- 
guage. The precondition for communlt)^, he thinks, means that certain 
Implicit standards are already in place. These don't specify how wc 

must act. They don't wield powder. 



248 Pfiihsnphy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

f: The matter scorns rather schizophrenic. The incthtxl is supposed to be 

neutral with respect^ say^ to relijjion, and j^'ct it is not a nculral ^uidc. 

O: Haberinas wouid want to argue that his methods are neutral, but that 
their findings arc not. 

J: It also seems to me that if no instance of justice is sufficient^ this is a 
version of perfectionism. 

S: I think that part of the difficulty comes from thinking that 'absolute' 
entails univcrsaltty- 

O: If it is true, lie argued^ it must be true for everyone and affect every 

aspect of life. 

S: 1 do not see wliy tlie fact that there are views other than my own is 
sufficient in itself to make me doubt my own. 

* - ■ ■ 

O: I agree that is the de fadn situatloHj but 1 do find it difficuk. If wc 
ivant lo speak of absolute truth what does 'true^ mean? 

H: We must remember that riorkhclmcr and Habcrmas were influenced 
by HegeL For them, art is not subjective preference. Art Is one stage at 
which truth appears. This emphasis is still in Adorno. Art and music 
are a kind of knoisiedge of the world. They arc not private spheres. 

O: Habermas seems to depart from this. 

H: Yes and that is problematic, since you can give no account of moral 
judgement if you say that the way forward is to be determined simply 

b\^ people's interests. 

Q: 1 read Mabermas as a kind of Kantian. He argues for universality as a 
regulative ideal^ but what he actually looks for is different, namely^ an 
appioximatioji to the good, Anyone should in principle be able to sec 
that and criticize it. So the aim shouldn't be identified with anything 
like the hig;iiest^ood. 

* - ^ ^ 

H: 1 think that is correct. 



Part VI 

Process Thought 



16 

Process Thought 

John B. Cobb, Jr 



'Process Lhought' can include a wade range of piiilosopSilcs and theologies. 
Hegel, for example, is clearly a process thinker. But the term has hcen 
used in receni limes to refer especially to the ideas of Alfred Xorih 
Whitehead and those who have heen influenced by him. In the philos- 
ophy of religion, the key figure beyond Whitehead has been Charles 
Hartshorne. In this essay I T.vill limit myself to those who associate 
themselves chiefly with the thought of IVhilehead and Hartshorne. 
This is the branch of process thought committed to cosmology or 
metaphysics. 

I thereby omit from consideration major schools of philosophy of 
rclijTLon closely related to process thought and sometimes included 
under the term. In the generation of HartshornCr there were also Henry 
Xefson Wieman, Bernard Meland and Bernard Loomer, all of whom 
found much of value in Whitehead, but drew equally on other sources. 
They, toOp continue to be intluential in the American scene. Some of 
their followers arc among the most articulate critics of the metaphysical 
and cosmological forms of process thought that i will repicscnt- 

The accent In this group is on the empiricalj the cultural and the 
historical If they are theislic at all, this feature of their lliought tends 
to be margiiiaL Criticisms of these branches of process thought are 
likely to be quite different from criticisms of the schooi on which 1 will 
focus- Nevertheless, there is a continuum between the t^vo f;roups and 
also a strong sense of relatedncss in a wider context Lhat rejects or 
ignores the radical empiricism and neo-naturalism that both groups 
have in common. 

In order to develop a focused paper, I narrow the topic still more. 
Among followers of VVliilchcad^ some have little interest in religion. 
Among those w^ho do, some have rejected his doctrine of God- Some of 



2Si 



2SZ Pfiihsnphy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

those who find much of wiluc in his cosmolo^' and metaphysics do 
not want to be encumbered by any form of theism- Others w^ant lo 
connect his cosmolog\^ and metaphysics to a different form of thetsm. 
They play an important role in process thought^ but lo include them 
here would be confusing. 

There is a further difficulty in identifying the topic of fftis paper IdHfee 
myself^ many of the followers of Whitehead and Hartshornc are the- 
ologians rather ihan philosophers. Of course, we face both ways. 
Among theologians we arc regarded as far too concerned with philo- 
sophical issues. They correctly judge that for us somewhat autonomous 
philosophical questions arc of crucial importance for the formulations 
of lailh. Among philosophers, of course, we are viewed with suspicion 
because of our theological commitments- The^^ are correct that our 
pliliosophlcal rellection is ultimately in tlic service of faith, although, 
in our vic^v; to be properly in the ser\ace of faith, such reflection 
should toe as open and rigorous as possible- 



1 



Whitehead's latest works arc those most influential among his current 
theological and philosophical followers. By the Lime he wrote these, he 
was out of step with the intellectual community. Both philosophers 
and theologians had rejected cosmotogical interests In favour of more 
nariowly defined disciplinary ones. Dominant streams of philosophy 
had become analytic or positivislic- Theology stressed its starting point 
In faith and its independence from all secular disciplines including 
philosopliy. Hence both philosophers and theologians criticized the 
efforts of process thought to attain a coherent view of the whole that 
did justice both to science and lo religion. 

In the effort to attain such a \1ew, dominant formulations both in 
^ience and theology had to be challenged- In otiier words^ instead of 
accepting the autonomy of the several disciplines^ process thought 
engages In erttictzing their assumptions and seeking to forniulale better 
ones. From its point of view, most of the disciplines operate with 
subsianLia^ist assumptions whlchn obviously, appear inadequate or 
misleading to process thinkers. This means that the metaphysical 
judgement of the primacy of event and relationship over substance 
and attribute is central to the project. These metaphysical claims have 
been pursued in a context in which^ in general^ both philosopticrs and 
theologians have been anti-metaphysicah 



jofu^B.Cohk Ir 25'i 



The most serious objections to process thought should be apparent 
from this account of its programme- It pursues a projeclj metaphysics^ 
which is supposed to have been shown to he invahdaled by David 
Hume and Immanuel Kaiil and maiiy others in the past two centuries. 
Ic seeks a coherent, inclusive \vtsion in a time when this has been shown 
to bo impossible asid, perhaps, oppressive as well. It ignores and con- 
fuses tlie boundaries bet^^cen the sciences^ philosophy and theolo^^ in 
such a way as tc deny the integrity of each. In short, it continues an 
effort that has been outdated since the late eightcentli century- 
Have these objections been met? Obviously, one who did not thint; 
so would not continue a project so out of tune with one's intellectual 
surroundings. Whitehead agreed with Hume and Kant thai early mod- 
em philosophy was fundamentally flawed, but he understood himself 
to be providing an alternative solution to the problem, an alternative 
that has been little pursued during the past tAvo centuries. 

This is not the place to develop the argument In any deialL But It 
may be wefl to say that Whitehead's doctrine of physical prehensions 
introduces a way of thinking about causality that was nol considered 
by either Hume or Kant. Those of us who arc convinced of the superi- 
ority of the resulting understanding of causality are not persuaded tay 
the arguments of Humeans and Kantians that cosmological and meta- 
physical thinking should be abandoned- These arguinents in general 
seem to be based on understandings of causality w^e do not share. 

On the other hand, VVhiteheadians have also been convinced that 
the cosmology and metaphysics that are now needed arc quite differ- 
ent from those that were dominant in the pasL Hence they have been 
critical of Thomists and others who continued to defend more tradi- 
tional views. The metaphysics that seems to us viahle loday on the 
basis of the evidence of both science and religious experience, as well 
as Intrinsic intelligibility, is a process metaphysics. This requires quite 
radical changes in the understanding of the human self and God as 
well as of the natural world. Obviously, proposing major revisions 
evokes ciiticisin from those who stay closer to the tradition. 

This criticism is at two levels. First, there Is criticism of the whole 
revisionist project. Some critics believe that the meanings of such 
words as 'God' are clearly estahlished in the tradition, cspecialtyH 
perhaps, hy St Thomas. The proper philosophical task is to debate the 
intcihgtiity of the idea and the justification for affirmjiijj that God, so 
understood, exists. Process thinkers reply that the traditional doctrine 
today shows internal incoherences and that it does iiol fit well with 
moral and reli^ous experience. To insist on maintaining it unchanged 



254 Pfiihsnphy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

invites the atheism that has, in factj been evoked in response to it. But 
to leave the allernativcs only as Itaditional philosophical theism, on 
the one hand, and atheism, on the otlier, has appalling consequences. 
Far more uscfLiI is the conslruclive task of tliinking about ivhat or 
wliom we can trust and worship today. 

At this level, the process response to the criEicisiii continues to com- 
mend itself to mc. But tlnere is another level of criticism which I take 
more seriously. Especially in an earlier generation, criticisms of tradi- 
tional theism by process thinkers were often harsh and lacking in 
nuance- Traditional theism was depicted as inflexible and monollLfiic. 
We now know that its capacity for internal self-transformation is far 
greater than we had supposed. We have learned that It contains greater 
depths of insight and is subject to more fresh interpretations than we 
had imagined- Tlie substance thinking to which it is attached does not 
{^ntail all the consequences wc projected upon it. There may have been 
sonic justification for the process polemic at one time^ in order Eo open 
up the discussion of neglected issues, but today simphstLc formulations 
of our differences from some of the revised forms of traditional theism 
are anachronistic- Differences remain, but process thought may not have 
provided adequate answers to ali the subtler challenges that characterize 
the current discussion. 

The other level of criticism is around particular doctrines of God. 
These are probably tlie best known debates in philosophy of religion 
invohang process thinkers. One of these is the process doctrine of divine 
mu lability. Metaphysically this follovs^ in process thought from the prin- 
ciple that to be actual is both to act and to l>c acted ujx>n. Every actual 
entity Is internally related to tts entire past. If God is actual, 
then God, too, prebends, and thereby incorporates, the past. As new 
events occur^ the past incoTporated by God grows. By incorporating that 
growitig past, the divine experience grows, too. Growth is a form of 
change; so^ for God to grow In this way presupposes some kind of divine 
mulabality- 

Process thought emphasizes that this form of mutability is compat- 
ible with, indeed requires^ another form of inuiiiutabLlity. God is ahvays 
including whatever happens in the world. Perfect receptiiity is immu- 
tably characteristic of God. It is not God's character that chanj^es, but 
God's character Is such that God is responsive to w^hat happens In the 
world- 

Although this is a metaphysical point implicit in the primacy of 
process^ both Whitehead and Hartshorne understood it to have exten- 
sive religious and existential Emportance- Hence process thinkers have 



jofu^B.Cohk Ir 255 



often polcmicizcd against the doctrine of divine immutability for reasons 
that arc not purely melaphysical. Because most of U5 aie Christian^ we 
have also appealed to llie Bible for isupporl and have argued that if Jesus 
reveals God^ then God suffers with us in our suffering. 

Critics have objected ihai this makes God over after our ima^e. It 
reduces God to finitudc_ The infintte cannot change. Tho5e for whom 
God is conceived as Bein^ Itself rtjccl the idea of God changing because 
it makes no metaphysical sense. They join in the charge against process 
thinkers of anthropomorphism. The object of worship must be radically 
differciiL trom us, not the human writ large. Also, they believe that 
a personalistic doctrine of God cannot he defended against critical 
questioning. 

During the period in which process theologians have been fighting 
this battle primairily at the philosophical level, others have done so on 
primarily Biblical and existential grounds. Dietrich Bonhocffer and Jucr- 
gen Moltmann are two of the most innueniial. The notion that God 
suffers with us has become almost a comnionplace in many Christian 
circles. HenccH at that levels the critical objections have lessened^ and 
process thcologyn in this one instance, seems to be on the winning side. 

The philosophical challenge, however^ remains. For many philoso- 
phers of religion the only locus In which they can affirm God is that of a 
metaphysical principle that is beyond all the distinctions that character- 
ize creaturely things. In their eyes^ process theism treats God too much 
like a creature, hideed, in Whitehead w-e read that God is a 'creature of 
creativity'- Of course, that phrase is balanced by oihcrs that show bow 
very dift'ctent God is from the other 'creatures' of creati\aty, but it is sig- 
nificant nevertheless. For process thinkers God Is an actuality or n beings 
not creativitj' or Being Itself. Although tiartsborne does not make this 
distinction, for him^ too^ metaphysical principles apply alike to God 
and creatures. God^s transcendence docs not have the radical metat- 
physical character that many philosophical theologians have affirmed 
of it. These thinkers object that such a being is not cliaracterized by the 
mystery^ and docs not inspire the awe and wonder that arc essential to 
the divine. 

This objection is furthered by a certain form of rclij^ous experience 
as well As personaiisttc, Biblical images of God have become less and 
less credible with the changing worldvieiv, many who rennain belie^^crs 
have accented the radical otherness and formlessness of God. The 
attractiveness of apophatic raysticisra has Increased. Tills is the way of 
negation. Precisely because of its negation of all images and concepts^ 
it is free from many of the charges of incredibility that follow any 



256 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'fii^oir m tta^ 21%i Century 

positive affirmations about God. It also builds bridges lo the Vcdantic 
tradition in India and Lo liuddhist practice. Those who have been 
socialized in this way find the affirmations of process thinkers^ at bcst^ 

a distraction. Tliis is a serious objection. 

My own response has been to build on the distinction niade by 
Whitehead between creativity and God_ Creativit)^ is the metaphysical 
ultimate^ and plays^ philosophically an analogous rok in Whitehead 
to Brahmati in Vedanta and Emptiness in Zen. So far as I can tell, 
Whitehead did not make these connections or affirm any religious 
importance to the realization that we are Brahman or Empty or 
instances of creativity. But it is e^^dent from the history of rellfjion^ 
thai there is great Importance in this realization, it is a quite different 
form of religious tife from the trust and worship that are more charac- 
teristic of the Biblical tradition and lliat are directed toward One with 
whom creatures have sonic interaction. Thus far 1 have found this 
response to a very significant challenge satisfying. 

The posittng of two ^iltimates'^ in its turn, raises a whole new set of 
objections- For many people 'God' is virtually synonymous with 'The 
Ultimate' or The Absolute' in awav that makes the notion of l"wo 'ulti- 
mates' inconceivable- My response is that by 'ultimate' I mean onty the 
end of the line In some order of questioning. If we ask after material 
causes^ the ultimate in that line is different from the ultimate in the 
line of efficicntj formal or final causes. 1 take it that creativity^ is the 
ultimate material cause of all that is, including God. That is, God^s 
'matter" is ercati\1ty. But God is ultimate in aEI the other lines of ques- 
tioning, hi the Uible God is not the void or the chaos from which all 
things are created. This does lead to two Gods. 

A second fealure of process thought Is the denial that God knows 
everything about the future- From the point of view of process thou^ht^ 
this is not a denial of omniscience^ since God knows all that is and the 
probabiEities of the future as welL There is nothing else to know^- God 
cannot know exactly what will happen in the futurCji since tiie future is 
now genuinely open- 

For those who defend the traditional doctrlnCj howeverj this Is a 
denial of omniscience, another rejection of divine perfection on the 
basis of process anthropomorphism, hor God not to know the future, it 
is ar^ed, cuts against prophecy and the assurance that dhinc promises 
will be fulfilled, for somCj faith is primarily the confidence that all will 
come out right in the end, and for these the denial that God knows 
that this will occur in the course of history is a tlat rejection of faith. For 
some, omniscience is an essential attribute of God, and this necessarily 



Jofm R. Cohk !i- ZS7 



includes knowledge of the future. For them, the God of process 

thought is not truly God at alL 

Those who liold to a fully deterministic reading of history have no 
difficulty ill believing in God's knowledge of the future. But many who 
liold to omniscience in this sense, also affirm the reality and importance 
of human freedom in shaping the future. In order to wock out the 
tension between these beliefs^ some assert that from the transcendent^ 
divine perspective^ all time already exists. Our human experience of the 
radical difference between past and future applies only to our creaturely 
perspective. 

Clearly^ this solution is not open to process thinkers. Neither is the 
detetministic view of events. The uncertainty of the future, and there- 
fore the impossibility of God's knowing exactly what will occur, are 
built into process metaphysics. For the most part, this is satisfying to us 
religiously and existentially as well as intellectually, [t unequivocally 
accents the importance of human decisions in the shaping of history. 

On the other hand, a real objection lies in the strength many gain 
from the assurance that^ despite all odds and appaient improbabilities^ 
in tlie end truth will prevail and right will be done. Process thinkers 
|oin in singing 'We Shall Overcome' as an expression of hope and 
determination, but we know that for others it is an expression of coiifi- 
dencc that God^s promises will he fulfilled regardless of what creatures 
do- The inability to support that assurance can be painful. Those of us 
ivho are Christian theologians recognize that there are biblical passages 
supporting an apocalyptic fulTilment of history which we must 
demythologize. 

The challenge is to find other ways of providing assurance. Process 
thought offers several. Firstn there is the assurance that whatever 
happens God is witli us, God loves us^ God accepts us, and all that we 
arc lives on in the divine life. Second, there is the assurance that in the 
cbiifse of^istory all our efforts count for something, even if the particular 
goals for which we strive are not attained. Third, there is the assurance 
that God works with us and through us in every situation to bring 
about what good there Is possible, and that this introduces surprising 
new hope and promise- Fourth, some process thinkers hold out the 
hope for continued personal life beyond the grave. 

These responses to the objection suffice for many of us. We can also 
argue thai maturity requires Lhat we accept responsibility for our world 
and not expect divine intcr\Tnti6n to set tilings right or rescue us from 
our destructive practices, liul whether any of this is an adequate response 
to the objection is hard to say. It is adequate for my own religious needs^ 



ZS8 Pfiihsnphy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

but I cannot speak for those who find themselves in intolerable positions 
of oppression. 

Closely related to the revision of divine omniscience Is the rcjecUon 
by process thinkers of the notion of divine omnipotence. We believe 
that the doctrine of omnipotence rests on a philosophically outdated 
understanding of causality, precisely the one that Hume and Kant 
found indefensible. The VVhitchcadian doctrine of causality as physical 
prehensions cannol result in a single entity being capable of totihy 
controlling everything. 

Causality is here understood as influence, as one entity flowing into 
another and thus participating in its constitution. But every event results 
from the joint inflowing of many past events. Xo one can displace all 
the others. 

1-iLrLhcrmore, although to a large extent an event is the product of the 
joint influences of the past, it is never entirely so. There is always an 
clcmeni of self -constitution as wclL That self-consLttutLon is a response 
to the physical prehensions that causally inform the event, but this 
response adds something, it supplements- 

Finally, God's role in each event is unique- To understand it, consider 
as the event in question a momentary human experience. God is not 
so much one physical influence alongside the personal past, the ffcsh 
impulses llirough the sense organs^ and the remainder of the body^ 
although God's presence may play a role of that kind. God's distinctive 
role is that of making a creative response possible. God provides alterna- 
dvc possibilities for response to the physically given situation and calls 
the occasion of experience to realize that possibility which, in that situ- 
ation^ is best. It is God's role to give freedom to that experience and 
responsibiliLy as to how thai freedom is used. Thus, "whereas past events 
compel us to incorporate aspects of themselves^ God^s primary role is 
persuasive. 

The power of persuasion is very different from the power of coercion. 
If iL were possible to speak of the ideal limit of the power of persuasion 
as ^omnipotcBicc'j process thinkers would be glad to appropriate this 
traditional word. But we have fouiid thaL the notion of omnipotence is 
bound up with that of coercive power We believe, on the other hand, 
that persuasive powder is the greater power. It is true that coercive power 
can destroy and kill, but only persuasive power can give life, make free, 
and evoke love. 

A^aln, those of us who are Christian theologians also believe that the 
revelation of God in Jesus is not of a monopoly of coercive power but 
of an ideal instance of persuasive power, liberating power, empowering 



John R. Cohk !i- ZS9 



powcjf- God's activity in huinan life sets us free and calls us to rcspons- 
bLlity. We find that this revision of traditional theism brings us closer 
to the Bible. 

CriUcs objiecl that in the Bihlc God is depicted as 'aLmighty'. Most of 
this widespread assumption follows from the translation of a proper 
name for God, ^Shaddai' a? almighty. There is no justification for this 
translation in the Hebrew texts. But it would be going too far to say 
that the svholc of the liiblc is on our side. Wc must admit ihat some 
of the actions attributed to God, especially in the earlier books of the 
Old Testament, as well as the last book in Lhe \ew Testament, imply a 
controlling power that does not fit well into process thought. 

There is still much work to be done on these questions. Controlling 
and persuasive power cannot be wholly separated, The diverse under- 
standings of divine powei in the Uihle have not been fully sorted out. But 
much has been done, and some advantages of process thought have been 
extensively displayed with regard, for example^ ilj itie problem of e\'LL 

The most serious ohjcction here, as in the case of the revised doctrine 
of omniscience^ relates to the openness of the future. For some Christians 
the assuraitcc that God has the posvcr needed to transform all thin;^ in 
tlie end is what is chiefly at stai-^e in the claim that God is omnipotent. 
Process thought cannot support that assurance. 

The understanding of the self is another area in which process 
thought profoundly revises the tradition. Even persons who are 
attracted to other aspects of process thought often find themselves 
unable to follow here. From the process point of view, this shows how 
powerfully our language has caused us to adopt substance lliinking even 
when wc arc not conscious of doing so. 

Process metaphysics requires us to recognize that the human person 
is the flow of human experiences. Alternately^ we may defmc the per- 
son as the tlow ot human experiences In conjunction with atl those 
other events that make up the human body, hi neither case i^ there 
any underlying self or T distinct from the experiences. The self or T 

I b 

lies within the flow of experience. 

The vast majority of Westerners habitually think of ihemselvcSn 
implicitly, as the subjects of their csperiences rathcrthan as elements 
within those cxpenences. if one spells out what is implicit^ the experi- 
ences are attributes of a substantial self tliat remains self-identical 
despite changes in the cxpcricnec^ The self that cxpcticnccs pain 
in one moment is tlie same as the self that experiences joy in another. 
A major objection to process thought is that it dissolves this substan- 
tial, underlyinjf self into the flux of experience. 



2^0 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

Have process thinkers responded adequately to this objection? If we 
do not suppose that we have^ then we must recognize Ihat the basic 
claim of process thought is incorrect. That has in fact led some to turn 
away. Others of us find that the process view is phenomcnologieally 
more accurate and that there are others who^ independently of com- 
mitment to process metaphysics, are finding this to be the case. VVc 
take comfort in the fact that Buddhists have supported this vicvv, lived 
with itp and gained spiritually from it, for thousands of years. 

This affinity of process thought witli Buddliisni provides another 
ground of objection, lliis time from Christians- Is not a major differ- 
ence between Buddhism and Christianity, they ast:, the depreciation of 
personal existence in the former and Its affirmation In the latter? Does 
not acceptance of the Buddhist denial of an underlying self lead to the 
depreciation of personal existence? Can that be reconciled with Chris- 
tianity? 

My response to this h£^ been to agree that Christians prize personal 
continuity through timc^ along with the responstbtlities that continu- 
ity engenders^ in ways that Buddhists ultitnately do not. But Christians 
need not understand this personal continuity as based on a self-identi- 
cal self underlying ihc process- histcad, we can view each momentary 
experience as maintaining continuity with a particular sequence of 
predecessors^ embodying them with some peculiar completeness^, and 
aiming at the continuation of this sequence Into the future. 

Phenomenologically. Buddhists do not deny that this occurs. Far 
from it. They know how very difficult it is to break these conncctlons- 
Bul they sec the spiritual gains that occur when the lack of identity 
through time is fully appreciated and the present cuts off its tics to past 
and future. They develop disciplines that help this to happen. Chris- 
tlanSn on the other hand^ can accent the positive values of identifying 
oar personal being with a particular past, taking responsibility for it, 
and committing the future of this personal being. Christianity and 
liuddliisrn then appear as complementary responses to the same mcta- 
pliysical situation rather than as metaphysically opposed traditions. 



2 



Perhaps the most serious objection to process thought is that it has 
engaged too little with other philosophies. It has functioned too much 
as a ghetto within the wider community. For example^ it has engaged 
too little with the other philosophies of religion represented In this 



jofu^B.Cohk Ir 261 



conference. This is a valid objection, but our ftilluic in this respect has 
more juslification than may Lnitialiy be recognized- 
First, process thouglil in the form of process theology has engaged 
quite extensively with other forms of theology. By Itself this has been 
an absorbing task, and it has involved us secondarily in interaction 
with philosophers of religion who enter the theological discussion. Of 
course^ even here, we have by no means engaged all forms of theolo^n 
and certainly we have not been remarkably successful in shaping the 
mind of the church] 

Second, process thought is inherently Iransdisciplinary and interested 
in interaction with thinkers in many different fields. We are interested in 
the implications of our basic stance for physics and biology as well as the 
social sciences- We need also to sec whether developments in these fields 
cut for or against our assumption of the primacy of events and relation- 
ships over substances and attributes. What re\nsions in our cosmolo^' 
do new developments lec^uirc? This loo is an absorbing and never com- 
pleted task. 

Third, process thought points toward the importance of practice. \"\t 
believe that it has contributions to make not only to theology, but also to 
the practical life of the church. We have written on Christian education, 
pastoral counscning. church administration and preaching. Articulating 
tliesc contributions and trying to implement them also take a great deal 
of time- Furthermore, this work in the church is only a tiny part of the 
work w^e ulsh we could do in the wider society in education^ in therapy 
and in political and economic life. I personally have become particularly 
absorbed in the critique of economic theory and practice and liave been 
privileged to work with a W^itehcadian economist in this field. 

Fourth, much philosophy, incljdlng philasophy of religion, seems to 
operate within rather narrow disciplinary boundaries- Our belief that 
the most important tasks confronting humanity arc not well dealt with 
Ln that way tends to make the discussion with philosophers less urgent 
than some other conversations. Of course, there arc many exceptions. 
Fifths the discussion with philosophers that ivould be most helpful 
to us would be about the points at w^hlch our brancii ot thought breaks 
av^^ay from the Euro-American mainstream. In this paper 1 have 
touched on that btielly with regard to the issue of causality. If other 
philosophers are willing critically to evaluate the Wlitteheadian idea of 
physical feelings^ we will certainly benefit from their help. But our 
experience has been that when we point out the Humean or Kantian 
assumptions underlying the way problems are formulated in much of 
recent philosophy and propose that there are better assumptions, our 



2^52 Pfiih.wphy ofRi'lii^ou m tta^ 21%t Century 

contribution is rarely appreciated. On the whole, process thinkers have 
dealt more scriousty with philosophers of other schools than Lhey have 
dealt with us. 

The criticism that Is most valuable to us is criticism of basic assuni- 
tions. For this reason the most challenging cnticlsm that has developed 
in recent decade? has been directed to our social location as process 
thinkers. This social location has been chicfiv in the North American 
university and oldlinc (read middlc-classl church. Most process 
tliinkcrs have been males of European descent. In other words, most 
process thought has taken place within the establishment. Further- 
moTCj the effects of this location can be seen in the issues that we have 
taken up and the way A-ve have dealt with them. 

This kind of criticism can be simply relativizing and disempowerin^. 
But it need not be IhaL White, male process thinkers can ask, and to 
some extent have asked, whether process thought as such contributed 
to their preoccupation with issues posed by the domitiant society or 
whether ttits was the consequence of our general socialization into uni- 
vcrsity and church- The answer seems to t>c mixed. On the one hand^ 
abstract philosophical questioning and even theological doubts are 
niueh more lil^cly to take place among the privileged than among those 
{hey oppress. That means that raising cosniological and metaphysical 
questions at all does express the privileged social location of most 
process thinkers. But ttiat social location is not responsible for the way 
those questions are answ^ered. Indeed, process thinking has more ten- 
denc}' to destabilize the establishment chan simply to supply justifica- 
tion for it. 

Furthermore^ some of the earliest stirrings of contemporary feminism 
made use of process categories. Although most process thinkers are still 
malCn the ideas tend to cut against stereotj'pically masculine habits of 
mind and to be much more supportive of feminism. The social loca- 
tion of process thought no doubt blinded most of its advocates to this 
tendency^ but as we became aware of these issues^ most of us have been 
supportive of the femtntst movement if not participants therein. 

The initial cncounlci; with Black and liberation ihcoiogians was less 
friendly. The suspicions based on our social location were justified, hut 
the content of our affirmations was more supportive of their positions 
than they realized- As we became clearer about the implications of our 
own ideas and as llbcrationists realized that wc were supportive^ 
alliances have to some extent replaced opposition. Fortunately for us^ 
from an early date a few Blacks and liberationists saw the potential of 
process thinking to contribute to their ends. 



jofu} B. Cohk Ir 26^ 



AlihouEh Interactians with feminist and libcrationist movements 
and examination of social location are not identical with wliat would 
be entailed In engagement with critical theory, I describe it because it is 
the closest we have come on any large scale to such engagement. This 
interaction has accounted, I think, for more significant changes in 
process thouglit than any otli(^r, with tite possible exception of ciivi- 
ronmentalism. Together these have contributed both to emphasizing 
engagement witli real issues in the world and to the approach to that 
engagement. Many of us feel that in these moves we are realizing more 
fully what is practically involved in our Iheoretical coinmilmcnls. 

Our engagement with deceit structive postmodernism has been much 
less. The pervasive importance of that movement in religious studies 
programmes and in the American Academy of Religion have made it 
impossible to Ignore. The use of deconslrucive melhods by feminists 
and liberationists has also drawn attention to it. So most process 
thinkers wMlh religious inictests have paid some attention to it. 

Furthermore, there are many feature? of deconstruction that are con- 
^eniah Much of what is deconstructed in ihe tradition is wliat process 
thinkers also have been trying to deconstruct with less success. This 
applies^ for example, to the idea of an underlying or subslaiiUal self 
discussed above. 

Nevertheless, there are deep differences. Deconstruct ive poslmod- 
emism carries forward the Kantian trajectory against every form of 
objectivity or realism- The natural world seems to exist only as it is 
constructed by various humans. The process view ;hat consciousness in 
general and human experience as a whole arise out of natural processes 
seems virtually unfoimulatalc hi deconstructive Lernis. Furtlierniore, 
tlie process project of coherent and unifying thinking is systematically 
rejected both as illusory and oppressive, and Whitehead's deconstruct 
tion of ordinary sensory experience into its two modes is ignored. 

David Griffin has been the process thinker who has engaged this 
form of postmodernism most vigorously. He has argued that by carry- 
ing forward to its consistent conclusions the late modern project of 
limiting reason and denying the i intelligibility of the world, it deserves 
the name most-modern rather than truly postmodern. He has pro- 
posed an alternative constructive postmodernism which deconsttucts 
tlie basic metaphysics of both early and late modernity and proposes a 
processivc alternative. The most sustained engagement of process 
thinkers with the issues of postmodernism is in Vaneties of Postmodern 
Theology, by David Ray Griffin^ William A. Beardslee and joe Holland 
(Albany: SUXY Press, 19891- 



2*4 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

Wittgenstein's Influence in the Anglo-Anicfkan phitosophicat scene in 
Ihc past half-cciilLir^'^ has been so Gxtcnsivc ihat It would be impossible 
not to engage it in some measure. Some process philosophers, such as 
George Lucas, have tried to present process ideas In such a way Ehal they 
coutd be understood and even appreciated inside the dominant discus- 
sion. Others have complained abouL the linguistic turn which tends to 
erect the implicit metaphysics of the Enghsh language into the ultimate 
arbiler. Still others have complained that the notion of ianguage games 
can be so interpreted as to provide a space for fLdelsm, But I am not 
aware of an extciided study of Wittgenstein himself by a process 
thinker^ svith the possible exception of Nicholas Gier 

The most promising development in the dlalog^ue with Wittgen- 
steinians is the serious and friendly work of Nicholas Reseller^ Process 
Mi'tiiphysics. This recent effort by a participant in the philosophical 
mainstream to understand and assess process thought opens the door 
to a kind of interaction that has been difficult in the past. The 'Special 
Focus on Analytic Philosophy' In a recent issue of Process Studies 
(VoL XXV) is atso promising. Whether these developments can open 
doors to worthirvhile interaction with WLltgenstemtan philosophers of 
religion remains to be seen. 

A good portion of the discussion of objections to process philosophy 
of religion in Part I dealt with classical philosophical theism. Charles 
Hartsliorne devoted extensive attention to the critique of that theism, 
and over the years theie has been considerable response. I noted that 
process thinkers such as he may be faulted for treating; this tradition as 
monolithic and falling to consider adequately the nuances and changes 
that take place tlirough time- This failure applies to some extent to 
response to more recent philosophers of leligion who continue the clas- 
sical tradition of philosophical theism but often with different accents 
and ar;^umcnts. NeverthclesSj from the perspective of process thought, 
as long as they affirm such key doctrines as divine immutability and 
omnipotence, the arguments tliat have long been trademarks of the 
process tradition are relevant. 

Reformed Epistenioloj^, at least in the person of Alvin Plantinga, is a 
contemporary exponent of classical theism. David Griffin gave consrd- 
ciablc attention to Plantinga's formulations in his work on the problem 
of evlL Griffin is currently dealln;^ sympathetically with Plantinga's 
claims that science should free Itself from its bondage to a materialistic 
worldvicw and open Itself to the h^^'pothesis of God's activity in the 
world. As a process thinkerj howcverj he objects to viewing this activity 



JohnR.CohkJr 265 



as external disruptton, and he proposes viewing it as involvement in 
each of the evenly thai make up the history of the world. 

Process theology shares with Reformed Eplstemology the desire for a 
coherent worldvicw that can be affirmed by Christians- It shades in the 
denial that the now dominant worldview in science is required for the 
advancement of science and in arguinj^ for irs reform. It shares in belief 
that the ChTistian perspective can play a role in proposing ways in 
which that reform can and should take place. But from the process per- 
spective^ Reformed Epistemology's claim that its revelatoiy starting 
point suffices for justifying its proposals^ as long as they cannot be dis- 
proved, is not justified by the fact that all thinking begins with some 
presijpposilions. For process thought, all proposals arise from prcsup- 
positionSj l>ut each must be justified on its merits in the arena of public 
discourse. 



17 

Process Thought - a Response 
to John B. Cobb,Jr 

Schubert M. Ogdefi 



One of the merits of John Cobb^s chapter is his deft and Fair-minded 
dcHinitation of what^ for his puEposes^ is to be understood by process 
thought'- Accepting his delimitation, which 1 have no trouble doings 
I would have to say that^ if I am a 'process thinkci' at all, I belong \d 
the same group of such thinkers to which he identifies himself as 
belonging, that is^ those who associate themsch'es with the thought of 
Alfred North VVliitehead and Charles Hartshornc in their concern with 
cosmology and metaphysics; wlio have a particuiar interest in teligion^ 
and thus in philosophv^ of religion and philosophical tlicolo^; and 
who pursue this inlercst^ not as professional philosopliei s^ but because 
of their ealting as Christian theologians. It will hardly seem strange^ 
then, if I also confess to sharing, to a considerable extent, the same 
point of \lew that Cobb represents in his chaptcr. 

Specifically, I view the place of process tlioughl on the twcntietli- 
ccntury intellectual scene In very much the same way; and I, too, would 
say that tlie usual objections to it are explained by its clear-cut differ- 
ences, formal or material, from other modes of thought in Imth philo3= 
ophy and theology^ tliat continue to be or liave become more widely 
influential. Formally, its theory and praxis of philosophy in a more 
classical sense as comprehensive critical reflection on human existence 
as suchj and thus as perforce having a critico-constructive fuiiction 
centrally involving metaphysics and etliics, put it decidedly at odds 
with all understandings of philosophy as having only the one function 
of analysis, as well as witli other pliilosophics thai arc anti-, non-^ or 
only semi-metaphysical. Materially, its insistence that process is the 
hiclusive category and that God is to be treated^ not as an exception to 



266 



Schuhert M. O^ien 267 

metaphysical prmciptcs, but as Lhcir 'chief cxEmplification' sots it no 
less sharply over agEkinsL Ehe classic^il and, in many ways^ still domi- 
nant traditions in both tnctaphysLcs and theology. 

But if I agree with Cobh^s account of the place of process thoijl^t 
and of the usual objections to it, I also accept his distinction between 
the two le^'cls at Vhlilch it is usually criticized and his differentiated 
assessment of the extent to which process thinkers have adequately 
responded to the criticisms. J, too, would say that the defence we have 
made of what he calls ^tbe whole revisionist project^ more or less effec- 
tively meets the usual objections to it^ while our responses to criticisms 
of our neoclassical metapliyslcs and philosophical theology can very def- 
initely be improved upon. One of the reasons for this, cei'lalnly, is just 
tlie reason he gives - that we can and should be more attentive than we 
have sometimes been to other revisions of classical metaphysics and 
philosophical ihtoiogy thatp while scarcely neoclassical, arc not otm- 
ouiily open to the same objections that have l>ccome the stock in trade 
of our polemic against more traditional kinds of thought. And ! can say 
this without changing my judgement that some of tlie most delil>crate 
attempts, by philosophers as well as theologians, to commend some- 
thing like a mediating position l^eLween classical and neoclassical types 
of theism do not stand up well to careful criticism (Ogdenn 1991). 

As for Cobb^s discussion of particular doctrines of process thought 
that are commonly criticized and his responses to the criticisms, here, 
again, there is much with which I agree. In fact, 1 feel very close to him 
in his frank admissions that there arc assurances associated with tradi- 
tional doctrines of God^s omniscience and omnipotence that process 
thought simply caitnot offer- But^ then^ [ also find^ as he does, that 
process thought Is by no means without its own assurance-i and that, 
with the possibility it opens up for at last dealing with the problem of 
evilj it is as satisfying religiously or existentially as It is philosophically. 

[Joyond all tiiis, 1 can also accept most of what Cobb says in the 
second part of his paper, including his specific responses to the third 
question about the extent to which process thought has engaged with 
the other points of view represented in the conference. Although I am 
not bothETtd^ as he is, by philosophies that operate within ^rather 
narrow disciplinary iroundarics'^ 1 do sliarc his )udgcment that process 
thinkers, on the whole, ""have dealt more seriously with philosophers of 
other schools than they liave dealt with us\ Not only are critics of 
process thought who have first taken the trouble to understand it 
exceedingly hard to come by, but some of the philosophers who have 
responded to it have stooped to outright parody and ridicule, tn my 



2^58 Phihsnphy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

own worK. ccrtalnLyn the critical factor determining the nature and extent 
of my engagement with olher philosophical points of view lias been my 
vocation and tasks as a Christian theologian. While this has in no way 
precluded entering into extensive discussion with philosophers as well as 
theologians, it has definitely limited such discussion to philosophers 
whose wofk has been significant for the theologians who have been 
my primary Gespmchs-partncf - not all of which work, mcidentallj^^ is 
represented in the conference- In any case, my own engagement with 
some of the points of ^icw that arc represented - notably, critical the- 
ory and Wittgenstein - has been rather more extensive than Cobb indi- 
cates to have been true of process thinkers generally- 



2 



For all my agreements with Cobb^s chapter, however, there are a num- 
ber of ways in which my own point of view is different; and my guess 
is that we would both lud^e thai at least some of the differences are 
not only real but important. Thus, if he can admit to sharing 'radical 
empiricism and neo-naturalism' with the other main group of process 
thinkers whose accent he describes as falling on 'the empirical, the cul- 
tural, and the historicar, I would have to speak more cautiously. What 
most impresses me about this group is less their radical empiricism 
than their p(?i?empiricism, their evident assumption that the only 
meaningful assertions, apart from those of logic and mathematics, arc 
empirical or merely factual assertions. And what I understand by the real- 
ity of God so radically transcends evcri^^thing in nature, taken either in its 
individual parts or as the collection thereof^ that any characterization of 
my understanding as 'neo-naturalism' could only lead to confusion. 

It is also clear to me that^ at certain points, Cobb and I have really 
different understandings of philosophy, including metaphysics and 
cosmology. As much as I sliarc the general Whttehcadian \^ew of 
philosopiiy as the criticism of abstractions, 1 do not understand such 
criticism, as he does^ to he an alternative to accepting 'the autonomy 
of the several disciplines'. To be sure^ philosophy in my view does have 
a proper critico-constructivc function witli respect to all answers to the 
existential question, religious and theological as well as philosophical; 
and. to this extent, philosophy may be said to cover some of the same 
ground as theology. But Lf this means that phjlosofjhy does indeed act 
as a control on die answers of theoloE5^ as wtII as of rcHsion, it in no 
way denies their proper autonomy; for the converse statement is 
equally true: theology and religion aTso act as a control on philosophy's 



Schubert M. O^iiet^ 269 

answers to the same existential question. As for the autonomy of 
science or the sciences^ I see no reason at all why philosophy should be 
thought to chatlcnj^c it. Even if phlEosophy may quite properly criticize 
presuppositions of the sciences tliat are philosophical rather than sci- 
entific^ it is [oglcally different from tlie sciences and so may neither 
control nor be con l rolled by them. 

Tills means, of course, that I discern a view very different from my own 
ivhcii Cobb talks about process metaphysics seeming "viable today on the 
basis of the evidence of Iroth science and religious expericncCj as wcU as 
intrinsic intelligibilit)^'. 1 do indeed think with Whitehead thai 'the best 
rendering' of 'that ultimate^ integral experience. ..whose elucidation is 
the final aim of philosophy' is 'often to be found in the utterances of reli- 
gious aspiration^ (M-liitchead^ 197S: 208}. And so 1^ too, would say that 
religious experience as expressed through religious utterances is very 
definitely primary evidence for philosophical, and, specifically, meta- 
physical and ethical reflection- But I cannot say the same for science, 
even though 1 quite a^ce that the conclusions of process metaphysics, 
like any metaphysics^ cannot l?c viable in the long run unless they arc 
compatible with the results of scientific research. 

The ex^x^rience of which I understand science to be the best renderings 
at the secondary level of critical reflection and proper theory, is not the 
'ultimate^ integral experience' of ourseh^es and others as parts of the 
encompassing whole, which 1 distinguish as our ^x!?itent!{il experience^ 
but rather our empirkn! experience, by which 1 mean our derived, 
external perception of ourselves and the world by means of our senscs. 
Thcrc is also the difference that, whereas the assertions of science, 
being properly empirical, must be at some point empirically falsifiable, 
the assertions of metaphysics, and therefore of process metaphysics, 
cannot be empirically falsified. In fact, strictly metaphysical assertions 
cannot be factually falsified at all, because theyfortnulate the necessary 
conditions of the possibility not only of human existence, but of any- 
thing whatever. On my understanding, then, to suppose that process 
metaphysics even could be viable on the basis of the evidence of sci- 
ence as well as of religious expetietice is to imply another, very differ- 
ent vaew of metaphysics as, after all, an empirical, or quasi -empirical, 
undertaking that differs from science only or primarily In Ehc scope of 
its generalizations. 

I shall say mote about this difference presently. But 1 first want to 
point to a couple of others that I take to be important. 

The first pertains to what Cobb speaks of as ''the rejection by most 
process thinkers of the notion of divine omnipotence'. Like other such 



270 Pfiih.'iophy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

thinkers - including, in soinc of his more recent statements, I regret to 
say, even Hartshoriic iHartshornc, 19K4) - Cobb so discusses ihis matter 
as to leave the impression that the very notion of God's omnipotence is 
mistaken. There are indicalionSj of course^ that what he really objects 
to is not the notion of divine omnipotencCj but rather the most com- 
mon way of construing this notion, or^ if you will, the most common 
way of talking about God's transcendent power According to this way, 
the notion of omnipotence is bound up with talk of power as coercive, 
and God is said to be capable of totally controlling everything. But foi 
all Cobb clearly says to the contrary, he can be fairly taken to reject not 
only this particular way of talking about divine omnipotence^ but any 
other way of saying that God's power over all things is tiie power^ the 
power than which none greater can be conceived. The contrast at this 
point witli his earlier discussion of omniscience is striking. Whereas in 
that discussion he clearly explains why, from the point of view of 
process thought^ "^the denial that God knows everything about the 
future... is not a denial of omniscience^ there is no comparable expla- 
nation in what he has to say al:*out God's power - to the effect that the 
dental that God can totally control everything is just as little a denial 
of omnipotence. My vicw^^ however^ is that there can and should be 
just such an explanation and that process thought at its best provides 
it. Instead of making it easy for critics w-ho allege that the God of 
process theism is tittle more than the well-knowii Tinite God' of certain 
modern philosophers and theologians, process thinkers have again and 
again made clear that and why In their understanding, the power of 
God, like everything else about God, can only be spoken of in such 
terms as 'ideaF, 'maximarj 'unfailing", 'infallible'j 'irresistible" - in a 
word, 'unsurpassable'. Thus f larlshorne, for one, having argued that 'no 
teleolog)' can exclude unfortunate accidents and frustrations, for goals 
have Lo be reached ihiough mutiple acts of freedom, none of which can 
Jk entirely controlled, even by God/ ^ocs on to add. The point is not 
that [God] cannot control them, but that they cannot be controlled, it 
is not [God's] influence which has limits, but their capacity to receive 
influence- Absolute control of a free being, and there can be no others, 
is sclf-contradlctorj^'" (Hartshorne, 1962: 81). But, then, omnipotence is 
not a mistake; the mistake is a merely verbal constmal of omnipotence 
that we have the best of reasons for rejecting even while holding that 
God's power as the alt-worshipful cannot be surpassed 

The other difference is closely related in that it has to do with Cobb's 
endorsement of Whitehead's view ihat "'God is an actuality or u beings 
not creativity or Being Itself/ He refers in this connection to Wiitehead's 



Schuhert M. Ogdm 271 

wclHtnown dislinctlon bct^s^ccii creativity and God and to his character- 
izations of God as 3 ""creature', albeit a unique crcalurc^ of creativity. 
But, surely, tf there L^ anything unchallengcably problematic in White- 
head's metaphy^tcs, U is just tliese characterizations - along with his 
closely parallel statements that 'God is the ultimate limitation', and 
God's existence, the ultimate irrationality' (Whiteheadn 1925: 2S7). 

Aside from the evident self-contradiction of saying that God is ^thc 
primordial creature', or the 'primordial, non-tcmporai accident' of cre- 
ativityp there is the dcepei difficuhy that neither God nor anything else 
may tae properly said to be a creature of creativltyn given Whitehead's 
own use of terms. He expressly states that ^creativity^ is his term for the 
ultimate spoken of somehow in all philosophical theory, and he defmes 
it as referring to 'the universal of universals characterizing^ ultimate mat- 
ter of fact\ He is also careful to explain that tlie creaiivicy thus referred 
to Is ^actua( in virtue of its accidents ... . and apart from these accidents 
i^ devoid of actuality'. But, then, according to 'the general Aristotelian 
principle\ or his own 'ontological principle', If there is no actual 
entity, there is no reason, because 'agency belongs exclusively to actual 
oecastons'p and ^apart from things that are actual, there is nothing - 
nothing either in fact or in efficacy' fl978: ^l, 7, 21, 40, 18K In other 
words, because 'creativity' refers to nothing actual, but only to the 
utmost of abstractions, it may not be properly said to create anything, 
nor may anything, God inckided, Ix^ properly said to he it^ creature. 
Thus, even given the distinction betVhTcn creativity and God, the only 
creators allowed for tn a consistently Whiteheadtan metaphysics are 
God and those v^lto, in a unique sense, may be said to be God^^ crea- 
tures, but not the creatures of creati^^ty. 

But quite apart from this clear implication of WhUMi^fd's own meta- 
physical principles, Hartshorne has long since given good reasons for 
saj^ng that God is and tnust be not only a being, but also Uein^ Itself, or, 
as he usually puts it, Troccss hsclf^ or even ^Creativity Itself. On this 
point, 1 fear, Cobb is simply wrong; for flartshorne not only accepts the 
distinction in question - repeatedly, in his many exchanges with Paul 
Tillieh - but also insists on it as necessary to his own understanding of 
God as ^the universal individual'. Tiod must, in spite of all difficulties^ 
he says, ""be a case under rules, he must l>c an ii~Ldividual iKing. riowevcr, 
he must not be a mere, even the greatest, individual being; rather^ he 
must also in some fashion coincide with heing or reality as such or in 
general.... [God's] uniqueness must consist precisely in being both 
reality as such and an individual reality, insofar comparable to other 
in divi duals' (Hartshorne, 1967:34 fj. 



272 Pfiih.^ophy ofRi'lii^mr m ttn! 21%i Century 

Of course, Hartshonic's admission Lhal God qim an individual is 
insofar comparable to other individuals confirms Cobb^s claim that, for 
hinij too, metaphysical principles apply to God as well as to creatures, 
liut it is misleading to say^ as Cobb docs, thai Hartshornc takes them \o 
apply 'alike' to God and to creatures; /or nothing is more important lo 
his ncoclasical Ihtism - or, I may add^ my own - than to insist that the 
difference between God and any creature is itself a catcgorial, or, as 
1 say, a iranscendcntaln diffcicncc. This means that God cannot be just 
an exemplification^ but can only be - In tlic most exact sense of the 
woids - the djjt^' exemplification, of metaphysical principles, the dif- 
ference between their meaning In this application and in every other 
being not merely a finite^ but an infinite difference- 

How effective insistin;^ on this is likely to be in meeting the objection 
that ""process theism treats God too much like a creature' may obviotjsly 
be questioned. But 1 see no reason to question either the difference or 
the importance of the difference between this ivay of responding to the 
ob|ection and Cobb's. 



Another more fundamental difference 1, at least, judge to t>c more Impor- 
tant, hi this case, how'evcr, it is a difference iiot only from Cobb's point 
of ^iew, but also from that of most, although not all, process thinkers^ in 
the delimited sense in which I^ too^ am using the term. It is because of 
this difference, indeed, that I signalled at the outset that whether i am a 
process thinker even in this sense is not a closed question, liut l>e this as 
it mayn the difference to which I refer pertains to yet anolher respect 
ii^ which Cohh's view of meiaphysics clearly seems to be other than 
mv own. 

For all he says to indicate olherwise, he fully shares the same panpsy- 
chlst, or, as Hartshomc prefers to say, psych icalist, metaphysics that cer- 
tainly appears to be implied by Whitehead's doctrine of prehensions. 
1 put it this way because some of Whitehead's formulations may be 
thought free of this ImpllcatLon - as vslien he says, for example^ The way 
in which one actLial entity is qualified by other actual entities Is the 
"experience" of the actual world enjoyed by that actual entit};, as subfect' 
(1978: 16th). On the other hand. Whitehead asserts unequivocally tiiat 
'the key nolion' from which construction of a metaph)-'sical cosmology 
should start is that 'the energetic activity considered in physics is the 
emotional intensity entertained in life^ (1938: 231 f.); and most ol his 
other fonnulations as well take 'experience' to be the expikuns, not the 



Schuhert M. Ogden 27}! 

exptk^f^ihtm, and may therefore be reasonably taken to assert or imply 
the same psych i call sm. In any casCn Harlshome's espousal of this kind 
of catc^orlal metaphysics is notorious, and, so far as 1 can sec, Cobb is 
like most other process thinkers in following him in this. This means 
that, as I understand it, Cotabs vIcvk^ also^ is that not only Godn but 
anything else that is actual and comparably "singular, as distinct from a 
TTicre a^grcgatc^ Ls, in its own content or quality in itself, some form or 
other of experience. 

Of course, what Ls meant by 'experience' here is not specifically human 
experience, or even animal experience more generally, buL experience in 
the completely penerahzed sense that Hartshorne calls ^exjx^ricncc as 
such'- In other words^ the category 'experience"" so used is supposed to 
function neither literally nor merely symbolically or metaphoricaUyH 
but anuh^icaUy, In tJiat it Is held to apply to all the different things to 
which it is applicable even within the same logical or ontologLcal type, 
not in the same sense, but in different senses. This is why there can be 
said to be many different forms of experience, ranging all the way from 
that of the least actuality that can be conceived to that of the grcatLst - 
to the experience of God. 

But it is just this supposedly analogical use of 'experience', which is 
required by the psychicalist metaphysics of most process thought, 
including Cobb^s, that I find unaccepLable. I^or reasons that I have 
developed at length elsc^^here, it is impossible to distinguish other than 
verbally between a so-called analogical use of 'experience^ and other 
psychical tcrmSn on the one hand, and their use merely as symbols or 
metaphors, on the other (Ogden, 1984). At the same time, the meaning 
of these terms when supposedly used as metaphysical 'analogies' can be 
really distinguislied from the other purely formal, literal concepts that 
they necessarily presuppose only by tacitly committing the pathetic 
fallacy of treating a merely local variable as cosmic or universal, 

Thus, to taltc Whitehead's point in the sentence quoted, one actual 
entity may be said to experience another if, and only It^ it is somehow^ 
qualified by, and therefore Internally related to^ the other actual cntity. 
In this way, the purely formal, liLeral concept ol" one actual entity's 
being internally related to another is necessarily presupposed by the 
meaning of one actual entiLy's experiencing another on any use of 
'experience^ including its supposed analogical U5e. The difficulty with 
aiiy analogical use^ however^ is that saying, as psychicalisls do, that all 
actual entities 'experience' others then cither becorhes empty, saying ho 
more than that all actual entities are intcfnally related to othcrSn c^r else 
can he taken to say more than this only by tacitly taking 'experience' in 



274 Phih.'iophy of Ri'lii^f^ir m tta^ 21%i Century 

some other, less fully generalized sense, Ihercby committing the fallacy 
in question. 

My conclusion from this reasoning Is thai the assumption of most 
process thinkers that there is a third, 'analogical use of psychicalist 
terms that is just as proper as their literal and symbolic uses is mistaken. 
But, then, since just such an analogicat use of somi' categoriai icrms, 
physicallst if not psychicalfst^ is evidently essential to any cate^crial 
metaphysics, 1 also conclude that no acceplablc metaphysics can be 
catcgorial^ but must be strictly transccndentaL 

This is not the place, obviously, lo explain adequately all that is 
involved in this distinction. Suffice it to say that, whereas a catcgorial 
metaphysics such as psychicatism or physicalism proceeds speculaLivclyr 
b^^ generalizing the meaning of certain terms until they supposedly 
l}ccome metaphysical analogies, a transcendental metaphysics dispenses 
with such analogies and proceeds strictly analytically by analyzing the 
ineaning of all terms with a \iew to explicating their necessari^^ presup- 
positions, the unconditionally necessary among which it distingiilsties 
as properly 'iransccndcntals'. Thus if the method of a catcgorial meta- 
physics is satd to be, in Whitehead's phrase, 'imaginative gcneralization^n 
the method of a transcendental metaphysics can be said to be 'presup- 
posltional analysis', or, taking such transcei:tdentals into account, ■"tran- 
scendental deduction' i^cf. Nygrenh 

In any case, the concepts and principles that a strictly transcendental 
metaphysics seeks to explicate arc purely formal, and so the terms for- 
mulating them are used literally ratlier than symbolically- This means 
that, within any of the different logical or ontological tjpcs in which 
they are applicable, they arc always applied in the same sense, net in dif- 
feretit senses. Thus, when 1 say, in the terms of my neoclassical trariscen- 
dental metaphysics, that God is the universal individual, this is to be 
understood quite literally, as ineaning both that God is literally an indi- 
vidualn and thus a centre of interaction with itself and other individuals 
and events^ ami thai God is literally universal, and so tiie individual, the 
one centre whose field of interaction with self and others is unre- 
Stricted and which, therefore, is just as Literally reality as such. 

That I say God is literally an individual, however, does not imply that 
I would call God literally 'a person'. A person must indeed he literally 
an individual because being a centre of interaction with self and others 
is a necessary condition of the possibility of being a person, not only 
literally but even symbolically. But the converse does not hold - not 
even, consistently, for psychicalists, who concede wlien pressed that 
'person', Ix-in^ by its very meaning a local variable, cannot be predicated 



Scbuhert M. Ogden 27S 

of God cithci literally or analogically, but only symbolically or meta- 
phorically. Unfofluiialclyn ihis concession docs not keep psychicalists 
from reverting to their usual habits and continuing to use 'person' and 
Avhat Cobb calls 'pcrsonalistiCn Biblical imaf;cs of God' generally as 
though they could be something more than symbols or mctaphors. 
Their justUicallon for this, presumably, is that thought and speech 
about persons^ being based primarily In our original, existential experi- 
ence of ourselves, others, and the whole, may indeed be held to provide 
more fundamental concepts and terms for thinking and talking about 
the whole than language based In out derived, empirical experience of 
ourselves and the world around us. Nevertheless^ once a distinctively 
analogical use of personalistic language is tuletl out as groundless and 
improper^ the only other possibility is to say candidly that God is not 
literally, but only symbotically or metaphorically a person. 

The virtue of a iwocla^Jiic^t transcendental metaphysics, however, is 
that it does not undercut, but raihct fully supports saying this, so that 
'offiy symbolically or metaphorically' need not have the disparaging 
implication that Paul Tillich, for one, so vigorously resisted. Because in 
the terms of such a metaphysics God can be Utcrally said to be the uni- 
vcrsaJ ii:idi^adual that not only unsurpassahly acts on all others as well 
as itselfp but is also unsurpassahly acted on by them, any talk of God as 
a person who loves and knows self and others, and so on is symboli- 
cally or metapliorically apt - as it cannot be given other metaphysical 
terms in w^hich God maybe lileraily said to act on all others, but is just 
as ]iterally said or implied uot to be acted on by them. 

But if symbolic or metaphorical talk about God as personal is fully 
supported by my Iransccndental neoclassical theism, it is in no ivay 
required by it. Consequently, if using 'God' in a proper iheislic sense is 
deemed to require stich personalistic talk, then iny designation of the 
tinivcrsal individjal integral to an adequate transcendental tnetaphysics 
as 'God'' is not properly theistk. In any events taking all talk about God 
as personal to be only symbolic or metaphorical obviates Cobb's 
recourse to distinguishing ^tivo '""ultimatcs'"'' as tlie way to take full 
account of nonthcistic as ^cll as theistlc religious ways of thinking and 
speaking about strictly ultimate reality What T understand Mahayaha 
Buddhists to refer to in distinguishing 'dlmrmijkiiya-iu^jiudme:^^' or, for 
that matter, Mei^tcr Eckhart, in distinguishing 'deita^\ is not the mere 
abstraction that crcatEvity' can alone properly refer to^ but something 
eminently concrete and actual - the one strictly universal individual 
that is at once the fathomless mystery and the ground of all rationality 
and that, as such, is the primal source and the final end of all things. 



276 Phih.'iGplTy ofRi'lightu m the 21it Century 

I should add, to obviate a possible misunderstanding that, on my 
analysis^ the main function of religious s^mibols or mclaphors is in any 
case not metaphysical but cxistcntlaL Although religious utterances 
perforce have mclapliysLcal presuppositions and impMcaEionsH but for 
the truth of which they could not themselves he true^ they are properly 
concerned with communicating the meaning of ultimate reality for us, 
as distinct from describing even symbolically or mctaphorical]y the 
structure of ultimate reality in itself. Accordingly, beyond claiming to 
be authorized, finally^ by ultimate reality itself^ ihcy mainly function to 
express and commend a certain way of understanding ourselves and 
leading our lives as parts of that reality. 

As lor the most serious objections to my view, I see two. The first is the 
objection also made to Hartshorne's metaphysics that to assume^ as I do^ 
that among the necessaiy presuppositions of our self-ui:iderstanding and 
life-praiis generally are certain unconditionally necessary ones that, as 
such, imply existence is to confuse necessity lie iikto with necessity 
de r?. But so far as I am able to judge, Hartshome's theory of 'objcctivo 
niodality'j according to which incxlal distinctions on the logical level 
correlate with temporal distinctions on the onlological level, effectively 
meets this objection- After all, confusion is one thing, correlation, some- 
thing else. And wliat metaphysics in my sense as well as liis assumes is 
not that logical necessity simply is ontological, but only that the two are 
correlative - necessary existence being what is common Lo all possibili- 
ties even as necessary propositions asserlLng sucli existence are implied 
by any proposition. 

The other objection is the one Hartshorne himself makes to my rejec- 
tion of psychicalism and the theism that is of a piece with it- To his 
mind, this rejection forces one either lo accept some other much less 
tenable metaphysics, that is, physicalism or dualism, or else to acquiesce 
in metaphysical agnosticism. Out what I reject, of course, is not simply 
psj^hicalism, but physicalism and dualism as well^ as equally unaccept- 
able insofar as they, too, are categorial rather than strictly tratiscenden- 
taL And so far as having to settle for agnosticism is concerned, my 
response is twofold- To know only that x must be Internally related to y 
is indeed not to know that x must somehow experience y. But it Is cer- 
tainly not to know nothing about Jt, and so 'agnosticism' It clearly is not. 
On the contrary, if 1 am right that any so-called analogical knowing is 
not really knowing at all, then Hartshornc's mctapliysics, for all its 
claims to know more than mine, must be equally ^agnostic'. Moreover, 
if the proper concern of metaphysics, like science, is with the structure 
of things, and in the case of metaphysics, their necessary structure, then 



Schubert M. O^iiei? 277 

it has every reason to abstract from, and in thai sense to be agnostic 
aboatn not only their meaning for us, but also tiieir own content or 
quality in Micmsclvcs. 



4 



Tlierc is one olhcr iinportanl difference between Cobb's point of view 
and mine that has to do with the philosophy of philosophy of religion, 
or^ if you will, prolegomena Eo iL, It is as clear from whal he does not say 
as from what lie says that philosophy of religion, in his view, consists 
primarily^ if not entirely, In the crltlco-con struct! ve task of formulating 
some kind of a rettjjious, not to say thelstic, cosmology or metaphysics- 
In my view, by conirasi, philosophy of religion, properly so-called, cither 
also has or entirety consists in another purely analytic task - th{^ task, 
namely, of critically interpreting the raeaniitg of religion, or of self- 
undcrstandinj? and life-praxis as explicitly mediated by religion, in the 
distinctive way in which philosophy generally critically Interprets the 
different forms of cuiture and Itfc-praxis. 

That way^ as 1 understand it^ is not simply to interpret the 'surface 
meaning' of particular expressions, as the other humanities, in tlieir var- 
ious ways, may be said to do^ but to analyze the 'deep structure^ or the 
'depth grammar', of all the different femrfs of meaning, so as thereby to 
disclose iheir 'tacit presuppositions' and to map their 'logical f^onlLers^ 
That the impulse behind such analysis, as John Passmorc insists^ is'meta- 
physical not linguistic' 1 take to be perfectly clear (Passmore: 78li_ But 
metaphysics is one thing, philosopiiy something else. And as certain as 
I am that pliilosophy docs indeed have the critico-conslructive task 
tl:tat Cobb assigns to philosopiiy of religion, and that carrying out this 
task centrally involves doing metaphysics as well as ethics, I would 
rather distinguish this by speaking of 'philosophical theology'. I use 
'philosophy of religion", then, to refer lo what cither includes or, In the 
strict sense in which 1 prefer to use the term, simply consists in philos- 
ophy's other essential task of analyzing the religious kind of meaning. 

The issue here, obviously, is not how we are to use certain terms. The 
issue is whether wc arc somehow to recognize the importance, if not, 
indeed, the primacy of this other analytic task in our discussion of 
'philosophy of jpjSigion 2(HJ0\ As soon as we do reco^ize it, however, 
we realize Ehat tliere arc some other and rather different things to be 
said from the point of view of process thought from anything Cobb 
has to say in his chapter. 



278 Pfiihsnphy ofRi'lii^mr m tia^ 21%i Century 

Of course, there can hardly be siich a thing as a distinctively ^process' 
way of aiiaiyzing tlic kind of mcaciing expressed by religious life and 
language. In direct proportion to its adequacy, any saeh analysis by a 
process thinker would need to agree in all essentials with any other 
adequate analyses by philosophers' working out of more or less different 
points of view. Even so, process ihinkers have devoted considerable tinif^ 
and energy directly to the philosophical analysis of religious meanings 
and some of their contributions arc^ in my judgemenl^ very much 
ivorth taking into account. 

Thus, for example, the South African thinker, Martin Prozeskyp 
although a philosopher rather than a Christian theologian, has interests 
in process cosmology and nielaphysics as well as in religion, comparable 
to Cobb's or my own. But most of his work^ as represented by bis book^ 
Rd{^k}f} ivid Uitimnte WeU-Seins^ an EApkJtuitoiy Theory, is concerned 
with analyzing Ihe meaning of religion and, as the subtitle indicates, is 
particularly directed toward idenl:if)rlng the factors^ cosmological as 
well as anthropological, necessary to explaining religion as a form of 
life and cullurc (Prozcsky, 1984; 19S6». 

Or^ again, I think especially of the work of VVilliani A. Christian, who 
is also, in his way something of a process thinker^ as is clear already 
from his early book on Whitehead's metaph)^ics ^Christian, 1959>. 
Most of his thinking and WTiting^ however^ are concerned precisely with 
what he callSj in the title of probably his best known book, 'meaning 
and truth in religion' (1964). In this book and in the iwo others that 
followed it, Oppa^ithfi:^ of Retigious Dcctrines {1972) and Doctrines of 
Reiigiou.% Cofmmmities U^H7), Christian contributes significantly to the 
purely analytic task of the philosophy of ireltj^ion- Indeed, in my own 
experience and reading, his clarification of the structure of religious 
inquiry and of the logic of religtous ar^ment remains unsurpassed. 

iJjl still more impressive, in my judgment, is Lhe contribution that 
Hartshornchas made to this others purely analytic task. At the heart of 
his account of religious utterances is the recognition that they are, in 
mv sense of the term, 'existentiar, and so at once clearlv different from 
Strictly metaphysical assertions and closely related to them. They are 
different from such assertions because, arising out of personal encounter 
with 'my God^H as he likes to say, as distinct from God as such, they 
either are or imply broadly factual assertions that are factually, even if 
not empirically, t'alsifiable. At the same timen they arc related lo strictly 
metaphorical assertions because they also imply assertions about God 
as such that eaamot he falsified either factually or empirically. By then 
elucidating the logical connections between these strictly metaphorical 



Schubert M. O^dei? 279 

assertions about God and other intuitively less problematic ones, such as 
^Something exists^ Hartshornc dircctl)' challenges the most fundamental 
assumption made by all parties to the debate on 'theology and falsifica- 
tLon' - thatn apart from the tautologies of logic and mathematics^ the 
only meaiiingful assertions arc factual assertions that can be factually, 
[f not empirically, falsified But more than that, he also defines a clear 
alternative to other so-called functional analyses that purport to show 
the meaningfulness of religious utterances without clarif)^ng how, if at 
alln their claim to truth is to be critically validated (Ogden, 1977). 

These few examples will have to do to make my final point. If I am 
right, they show clearly enough that process thinkers as a group^ far 
from having only one string to their bow, have, in their ways^ con- 
tributed tc both of the tasks of the philosophical study of religion 
200tX 



Bibliography 

Chrislianr W.A_ ^1959] .4ia Interpretnlion of Whitehead's Metaphysics, rs'ew H^ven: 

\a!c University Press. 

(19&4) Metiniug ami D'ltth m Rt^U^ion^ Princeton: PrinceTnn University Press. 

(1972) Opp^fsitions of Retlgious DGClmies: a Stiuiy w tije Logic of DLilo^ite 

among Reiigioiii, New York: Herder and Herder. 

(19B7) Doct^'iu^s ofReSl^iou^ ConfWiuiitii^s: a PhilGsophiciiI Stu^iy, New Haven: 



7ale University Press. 
Hartshorner C. U9623 'The Modem World and a Modern View of God'j The 

Cnme Review, 4^ 2- 73-35. 

11967) A Nntiiml Hieoh^fbr Our TJme, LaSalle, IL! Open Court. 

(19B4) Ofjifhpot(^nce trnd Other Th^vfopcal Mii:Likes, Albany^ State University 

of New Yoik Pies:*. 
Nygren^ A_ U572) Meaning and Kii'thod; ProiL'gomeua to a Scientific Philosophy of 

Rt'h^^io^? ami it Scte^ttsfic Thi^(A\^; trans. Philip S_ Watson. Philadelphia: Fortress 

Press- 
Ogden, S.M. fL977; 'Linguistic Analj^sis and Theolog>-^ Th^^olopacht^ Zeitschnfi, 

(1934) 'The Experience of God^ Critical Reflections on Hartshome's Theory 

of AniiEogy", in Exhtasc^ ami Actuniity: ConveFstitioiis wid} C^htirles Hmtshtm^Cf 
eds j.B. Cohbj JL and i\h Gamwell, Qircago: University of Chicago Press^ 
16-42. 
i:l991J 'MuKt God Be Really Related to Creatures?', Profe's'i Studies^ 20, l: 



S4-6. 
Pa^smorCr JoLiii (1961J Ffsiiosophicai Rta.itmf}i}^. London: GeraEd Duckworth & Co, 
Pfozesky^ Martin (,1984) Ri'hgsQff ami Ultimate Weil-B^in,g: an Exphviatory Theory, 

New Yorki SJ, MarEJn's Press. 



2S0 Pfiih.wphy ofRi'lii^mr m tta^ 21%i Century 

Prozesky, Maitin (1986) 'Philosophical Cosmology and Anthropology in the 

Explanation of Rtrligion', Theori*?, 66: 29-39- 
Whitehead, Alfred North (192-5) Scie^ict? and the Miytiem Worid, N€w York: 

Macmillan Co. 

(19.^S> Modci GfTfitw^^it, New York" Macmillan Co. 

Il978f Prt}c^ss in Rcaiity: ^in Es.^ify in Co^niotogy, ed_ D,R. Griffin and 

D.W_ Sherburne, New York: Tree Press, 



2 

Philosophical Theology at 
the End of the Century 

Wiiiiam /. Wainwright 



Many writers have commented on the Ecvlval of philosophical Lheolog^^ 
that began in analytic circles in the 1960s. Those of us who received our 
training in the 50s were reacting lo lwo things. Firsi, our predecessors"" 
preoccupation with the question of religious discourse's meanlnRfulness. 
While not necessarily disagreeing ^vith Uasil MilchelFs^ say, or John 
Hick's responses to Antony Flew's charge of 'death by a thousand qualifi- 
cations', most of us lost interest in the debate- Second, a conviction that 
Hume's and Kant's vaunted critiques of natural theology didn't with- 
stand careful scrutiny. On the positive side, developments in modal 
logic, probabilfty theory, and so on, offered tooh for introducing a new 
clarity and rigour to traditional dispuEcs. Alvin PJanlinga's work on the 
ontological argument, or Richard Swinburne's use of tJayesian tech- 
niques to formulaic his cumulative argument for God's existence^ arc 
paradigmatic examples- 

I have no quarrel with the main outlines of Swinburne's account of 
this development. Indeed, his own work is an exemplary instance of it- 
I do, however, believe it is incgniplcLe in live ways. 



Swinburne doesn't comment on the renewed interest in Lhe scholas- 
tics, and in se\^enteenth- and eighteenth century philosophical Ihcol- 
ogy. Swinburne's and Plantinga's work has hcen less visibly affected by 
this current. But Norman Kretzmann's and Eleoiiorc Stump's work on 
Aquinas, Alfred Frcddoso's and Thomas Flint's discussions of Molina, 
William Rowe's use of Samuel Clarke, or my own examinations of 
Jonathan Edwards are examples of an Important strand in contempo- 
rary analj^ic philosophy of religion. In each case, analytic techniques 



21 



22 FtsUGSf?piiy ofRiiti^kvi w the 21st Century 



arc employed to recover the insights of our predecessors and apply 
ihem to contemporary problems. 

These historical inqiiiiies were partly motivated ]jy the discovery that 
issues central lo the debales of the I9b(>s and 70s had been already exam-^ 
ined with a depth and sophistication sorely missing from most nine- 
teenth- and eariy ti%^entieth-centur)'^ discussions of the same problems. 
Two examples will suffice. By the end of tlie 60s it was clear that reports 
of the death of the ontologlcal armament had been greatly exaggerated. 
Charles Hartshorne and ^3orman Malcolm were suddenly not alone. 
A spate of articles appeared attacking and defciTiding modal versions of 
the argument. Many were quite sophisticated. Yet an examination of, 
say, Henry More, would have shown that Ehc authors of these arlieles 
were often reinventing the whecL For an insistence on the superiority 
of modal versions of the argument and the Importance of the possibil" 
ity premise (that a perfect bcin^ is logically possible)^ perfect devil 
objections, and so on, are all found in More's Anthiote dgninst Atiit'ism. 
More^ however, is still not widely known among analytic philosophers 
of reli^on, and his most important points were independently made 
by contemporary philosophers of re[i;^ion- Another example, though, 
illustrates how historical studies sometimes aJvaficeii contemporary 
discussions. Modern interest in the freedom-foreknowledge debate 
was largely reawakened by Nelson Pike's 'Divine Omniscience and 
Voluntary Action' which appeared in The Philowphlcnl Review in 196S. 
Marilyn Adams proposed a solution to Pike's puzzle which she (eor-' 
rectly) claimed to have found in Ockham, and Ockhamist solutions 
continue to constitute one major response to the problem- Alvln 
Plantlnga offered another solution which turned out to have been 
anticipated by Molina. Freddoso's and Flint's refinements of ^iolinism 
are another popular resolution of the dilemma. With the exception of 
tlie problem of eviln no other puzzle has so dominated journal litera- 
ture in the past thirty years. It is therefore instructive that sophisticated 
reconstructions of Oekham and Molina^ have played an important role 
In this debate. 

Yet there is another and, I thiiikn equally important reason for the 
renewed interest in our predecessors. A significant number of analytic 
pliilosophers of religion are practising Christian or Jewish theists. 
Aquinas, Oekham, Maimonides, Clarke, or Edwards are attractive models 
for Uiese theists for two leasons. Firsts there is a broad similarity between 
their approaches to philosophy and that of our contemporaries; precise 
definitions, nice distinctions and rigorous arguments are features both 
of scholasticism and of analytic philosophy of religion. But, second, 



the work of these predecessors was self-consciously Jc^vish or Christian. 

A coiivicllon of the truth and splendour of Judaism or ChristiatiUy 
ppn^ades their work. They are thus appealing models for contGmpotary 

philosophical theologians with similar commitments. 



Swinburne's characterization of the Ihrust of contemporary philosophical 
theology (including his own important work) is inadvertently misleading 
in al least one important respect. He focuses upon its attempt Lo 
defend two theses: fl) That the concept of God is coherent, and that 
(2) God so defined exists, fliese two concerns arc, indeed, tlic thrust of 
Swinburne's own early work, and dominated discussion in the first 
fifteen or so years of the period we are examining. Xor has interest in 
these theses died out, or the last important word been said- (Recent 
work on the evidential problem of evil by Rowe, Paul Draper, William 
Alston, Peter Van inwagenn and Swinburne himself are examples. 1 It is 
nonetheless true that the interests of philosophical theologians have 
broadened in a number of interrelated ways. 

In the first place, the array of topics is much wider than an uninfomied 
reader of Swinburne^s paper might infer. Since the 1980s Christian philo- 
sophical theologians have turned their atteniion to such specifically 
Christian doctrines as the Trinity, the Incarnation, and the Atonement- 
The essays collected in i-liHosophy nixd the Chmthm Faith are one 
example-^ Swinburne's ovvu w^ork on the Ttinity and the Atonement is 
anotlicr. 

Tn the second place, many of these philosophers wish to do more 
than defend the colicrence and rational plausibtlity of the doctrines in 
question. They are interested in their hcarinj; on problems internal to 
tlie traditions tliat include them. Tlius^ Marilyn Adams has argued that 
Christian philosophers should explore the implications of Christian 
martyrdom and Chrisfs passion for the problem of eviL in tier view^ 
suffering can be a means of participating In Christ, thereby providing 
the sufferer with insight into, and communion with, God's own inner 
life. Or consider Robert Oakes^ who contends that Isaac Lucia's doctrine 
of God's tzimzum (withdrawal) casts light on the existence of evil:^ 

Finally, a number of these philosophical theologians arc convinced 
that theistic doctrines can help solve problems in other areas of philos- 
ophy. For example^ Del Katzch has argued that if cialural laws are 
regarded as expressions of God's settled intentions with respect to the 
natural world, that is, as descriptions of His hal^itual manner of actings 



24 I'hUt7^f?piiy ofRiiti^kvf w the 21st Century 

one can account for their 5ub|iinctivc character (Ihc fact that empirical 
laws aren't mere constant conjunctions, as Hunic thought, hut support 
appropriate countcrfactuals). Christopher Menzel ha-s attempted to ^how 
that numbers, sets, and other mathematical objects can be interpreted as 
products of God's mental acti\1ty, and that doin;^ so illuminates them. 
Robert Adams and others think that a suitably nuaiiced divine com- 
mand theory can do a better job of accommodating two apparently 
conflicting intuitions: that moral values exist in minds, and that 
morality can command our allegiance only if it expresses a deep fact 
about objective rcality, 

3 



Swinburne's account of philosophical theolog>' creates the (perhaps unin- 
tended) impression that lis primary role is apologetic. Thcistic proofs, 
ar^mcnts for the necessity of the Atonement, and so on^ are addressed 
to non-bclievcrSj or to the non-lx^liever in us tpage 2). Yet if this is their 
main purpose, their value is limited, and this for two reasons. 

(1) Apologetic philosophicaE theolo^^ flourished in the early modern 
period. One thinks of the lioylc [ecturcs^ for example^ or of the work of 
Samuel Clarke or William Paley. ]iy the end of the eighteenth century, 
however, apologetic arguments had lost much of their power to per- 
suade educated audiences. Those who (like Coleridge and Schleierma- 
chcr) wished to commend rcliKion to its cultured despisers^ adopted 
new approaches. Their repudiation of philosophical theology was no 
doubt partly due to bad philosophy. (Kant's critiques of the traditional 
thcistic proofs^ for instance, aren't clearly cogent.l It was also the result 
oi'a Zeitgeist Khich extolled sentiment and feeling and denigrated 'mere 
ratiocination'. But whatever the causes, the fact is that the arguments of 
philosophical theology no longer produced widespread convicQon in 
most university-educated audiences (that is. in the very people who, b^^ 
education and training svcre^ one would think, best qualified to evaluate 
(hem). They thereby lost a large part of their effectiveness as apologetic 
tools. Whether they have regained it seems doublfuL (Note tliat this is 
not an argument Ehgainst employing philosophical theology as an 
apologetic took Rational arguments may persuade some, strengthen 
(he conviction of others^ and convince non-believers that theistic 
beiief is not irrational) 

(2) A second reason for thinking that philosophical theology's apolo- 
gctic value is limited is that it can't produce fhith.'^ Let me approacli 
this point b)' commenting on two observations of Swinburne's. He 



WiUmnf. Wciimvii^hl 25 



responds to the charge thaL cogent thcistic arguments would only 
persuade 'a prudent person [to] try to do what is good out of self-interest'^ 
by asserting that the good, while probahle, isn't certain, and ^the pru- 
dence of seeking such a good despite risk of failure^ is virtuous' (page 9}. 
Jonathan Edwards, however, thought that prudence or enlightened self- 
interest, like natural pity^ m}7 itself virluous although its absence is a 
symptom of ^icc.^ Charity, or true benevolence^ is alone truly virtu- 
ous.*" Or consider Pascal who believed that a eoinmllment based on 
prudence alone has no intrinsic reiighus value even though it cnti lead 
to action which produces genuine faith. Properly formed rctigious 
beliefs are expressions of a heart transformed by God's love. Prudential 
calculations may induce people to place themselves iii positions where 
God will stir their affections, but they can't do more than vliis. 1 believe 
that this is correct, and that what is true of prudential arguments is 
also true of the apologetic arguments of philosophical theologj^. They 
can break down resistance to falth^ and even produce belief^ Cut they 
cani produce the theoEogica] 'Virtue of faith. Why not? 

Consider a second comment of Swinburnc^s: Religion' doesn't 
'require more by way of belief than 'an uncertain belief open to revi- 
sion' (psg^ ^1' Notice, though, that this is at variance with both 
Aquinas^s and Calvin's insistence on faith's certainty. Thus^ Cah^in saj^ 
tJiat Taith is not contented with a dubious and fickle opinion.... Ilie 
certainty which it tequircs must be full and dccisive.^^ Aquinas is more 
careful. Even though faith is certain with respect to its object or causGn 
it is not fully certain with respect to its subject- Taith may accordingly 
be said to be greater in one man than another either when there is 
greater certainty and firmness on the part of the intellect, or whcii 
there is greater readiness, devotion^ or confidence on the part of the 
wLll/^ But Aquinas, too, clearly thinks that either a lack of readiness^ 
devotion, or confidence on the part of the will or a lack of ceitainty 
and firmness on the part of the intellect are theological ^ices. Merely 
probable opinion isn't sufficient. 

Now, fMce Aqutnas, this certainty and firmness can't be produced by 
philosophical proofs. Calvin thought that 'without the illumination of 
the Spirit^ the w^ord has no effect^^^ He would say the same, I thinks of 
natural theology, ^^ My pointy again, is not that philosophical theolog^^ 
is useless but that its vakie is limited. A probabilistic conviction that 
Qod exists, has certain attributes, and has acted in certain ways, isn't 
what the tradition has meant by the intellectual component of faith. 
Faith involves a firm cusunmce of God's goodness and favour towards 
us, and this isn't produced by philosophical thcolog)^^^ 



26 fhUo.wpiiy ofR^ti^w}! w the 21st Century 



4 



Thcistic arguments can tac used apologetically hut other purposes may 
be more important For example, thcistic proofs are sometimes used 
to settle disputes wilhtn a common tradition. Udayana's theistic argu- 
ments were not onlv addressed lo fellow devotees of Siva but to 
Mimamsakas in hi^ own Hindu tradition who inlerprctod the Vtdas 
athcistically. Again, al-Ghazali employed a version of tlie Kalam cosmo- 
logical argument to show that Averrocs' and Avicenna's interpietation 
of the Quran w^as heretic aL^^ 

Uut philosophical thc«lo^ is also employed devottonally. Tlius, 
Udayana's Nyayakusumaniali (which can be roughly translated as a 
bouquet of arguments offered Lo God) has three purposes - to convince 
unbelievers, to strengthen the faithfiil, biit aho to piease Siva 'by present- 
ing it as an offering at his footstools Regardless of the success Udayana's 
arguments may or may not have had tn achieving his first two goals^ 
tl:iey have value as a gift offered to God; their construction and presen- 
tation is an act of worship. Nor is that fact that Ansclm's Pmsh^ofi is 
east in the form of a prayer accidental. ■^'^ His inquiry is a divine-human 
collaboration in wliich he continually prays for assistance, and offers 
praise and thaiik5gi\ang for the Eight he receives. Anselm^s project as a 
whole is framed by a desire to 'contemplate God' or 'sec God's face'- 
His attempt to understand what he believes by finding reasons lor it is 
simply a me^m.^ to this end. 

Swinburne w^onders 'why so much cnerg}' was put into the project of 
philosophical theology-' in tlie medieval west when we might suppose 
that there was no more [and perhaps less] need of it than in earlier cen- 
turiesV He suggests that (he answer may be that the mcdievals were 
■■providing tools to deal with' the 'bit of sophisticated atheist in most 
believers' (page 2). I suspect^ however^ that the answer is quite differ- 
CTTil, namely, that medieval philosophical theology wasn't primarily 
apologetic in intent^-"^ but was, instead, a tool for settling intramural 
disputesj^^ and (most importantly) furthering the project of contem- 
plation by helping the faithful understand what they formerly only 
believed. The fact that philosophical theology seems to flourish best in 
ages of faith suggests that that project may be its primary purpose. 



The medieval project (inquiry as a means to contemplation) has 
another feature that is especially prcni[nent in Augustine and Anselni- 



WiUmnf. Wciimvii^ht 27 



Emotional and volitional discipline are as necessary for its success as 
intcllccLLial discipline. Ansclmc's inquiry^ for Inslancc, is punclualed by 
prayers to arouse his emotions and stir his wiil_ And this brings me to 
the tast way in which I think Swinburne's picture of contemporary 
philosophical theism is incomplete- it pays insufficient attention to the 
bearing on pliilosophical theology of the episleniological turn in the 
analytic phiEosophy of teligion. Reformed epistcmology's defence of 
the proper basicality of theislic belief isn't the whole story. Linda 
Zagzebski maintains that warranted beliefs are expressions of virtues- 
C. Stephen Evans and Jay Wood suggest that faith may be a necessary 
condition for appreciating certain reasons for religious belief. 1 have 
argued that a properly disposed heart may be needed to apprcciaLe the 
force of the evidence for theistic belief. Rea.wn {ind the Heart discusses 
Jonathan Edwards', John ftenry Newman's, and William James's 
reasons for Ihinl^ing that U is. Pascal^ I think, had a similar view. Pascal 
believed that Christianity provides the best explanation of hunianit/s 
'greatness' and 'littleness^ its wretchednesSn and the ambiguity of the 
tlieistlc evidence. He also thought that there arc good arguments from 
traces of design, saintly lives, and the fapparcnt) occurrence of miracles 
and fulfilled prophecy. This evidence is offset by instances of apparent 
disorder, evil or wasted lives^ and reasons for distrusting miracle reports 
and prophetic claims, and so won't convince everyone. Nevertheless, it 
IS sufficient to convince those who seek God or 'have the living faith in 
tlieir hcaits\'^ 

T will not repeat the arguments of my book here but simply note two 
relevant claims. Firsl^ what James called our 'passional nature^ unavoid- 
ably inflects our assessment of complieated bodies of evidence for ethical^ 
metaphysical, and religious propositions.^^ Since we can't escape its 
influeiice, claims to have dispassionately surveyed the evidence for 
propositions like these are Illusory.^'-' ^ccond^ views lit;c Edwards's or 
Kewman's or James's or Pascal's may be the only effective w^ay of defus- 
ing relativism, if there really are cthlcalj metaphysical^ and religious 
facts, and w^c have the ability to discern them, lack of progress and per- 
sistent disagreement between equally sophisticated and w-elUdlsposed 
Inquirers^* is surprising. In the absence of an explanation that is con- 
sistent with the objectivity of truth and the reliability of our epistemic 
facuTties, relativlstic conclusions seem called for_ Views like Pascal's or 
Edwaids^s provide such an explanation. If certain dispositions of the 
heart are needed to reason rightly about religious matters, then deep 
disagreements are likely oven if the relevant truths are objective and 
our epistemic faculties are reliable when functioning as they should. 



2S rhUGSf?piiy of R^ti^kvf w the 21st Century^ 

For some will possess the appropriaEc dispositions and others will not- 

So in the absence of a better explanation, non-rclalivists have a power- 
ful motive for thinking thai some theory of this type is true. 

The view I have just described is bolli similar and dissiinilar to 
evidcntialist projects like Swinburne's and to Reformed epistemolog)^ 
(or, in any case, to Ptantmga^s version of it). It is dissimilar to the first 
]&ecause it denies that arguments like Swrnburne's are sufficient to per- 
suade all fair-minded inquirers who have the necessary information 
and intellectual equipment.-^ It is dissimilar to the second in its insis- 
tence that the properly fortiicd religious bchcfs of mature adults arc 
typically based on e\1dcnce (albeit of an informal ktiid).-^ My inten- 
tion here^ however^ is not to defend these views but to call attention to 
the fact that the epislemological investigations of contemporary ana- 
lytic philosophers of celigion have a direct tjcaring on the enterprise of 
philosophical theology. If they are rights an adequate account of its 
persuasiveness or lack thereof must pay due heed to the heart. 

Let ine conclude with the point with which I began. 1 have no quarrel 
with the vast majority of what Swinburne has said. He has accurately 
described the thrust of much contemporary philosophical theology, 
and his own work is an exemplary instance of It. I thinks however^ that 
the contemporary scene is richer than his remarks might lead the 
uninitiated to believe. I have attempted to explain why. 



Notes 



L A5 well as of Aquinas and Jonathan Edwards. 

2. Thomas V. Morris (edj, Pfuh.iopiiy ami ti}t Christian Fiilth iKotre Dame^ IN: 
Univers-ity of Notre Dame Press., 19BB)_ 

3- 'Creation as Theodicyi a Defense of a Kabbalistic Approach to Evi(^^ FiUtli nini 
PSiHa.'iophy 14 {Octobei 1997j; 31C>-2I. 

4- for Swinbiinie on faith 7ic^ hlsFaitfr amiRttison [Oxford: Clarendon rress, J9SL3_ 

5. V3C60U5 jiassions can blind us to our true inrerests |ust as they can sometimes 
St 3 fie pity. 

6. Edwards more or less makes this point in Ti\i: Niitwe t^fTniL' Virtue, in PauJ 
Ramsey ^ed.^J Ethictif Writings, Works of Jonathan Edwards, voi. 8 iNe^v 
leaven L Yale Univeisity Press, ]9S9>, ch_ 7. 

7. Or^ perhaps more accurately^ a belief that God's exisEencSj say^ or Christian 
theism is nrtore likely than not. 

S. Ifiitittiti:^ ofthtf Ciuistiafi R^ii^ioif {Grand Rapids: Eerdman's, 1957J, Book iii., 
"Cli. ii. no, 15. 



W^sUmnf. Wciimviigtit 29 



9. Sunmm Tfji^ologica, 22ae, Q. 4, A. S, and Q. 5, A. 4. 

10_ Ifutitiiti^s. Book iiir ch. ii, no_ 33_ 

11_ And even Akjuinas'^ opinion on thts point is. more complicated than these 
remarks suggest. He sa^^s^ for exampiej that miracles and other external 
signs aren't sufficient to induce belief "for of those who see one and the 
same miracle, or hear the same prophecy^ some will beEieve and others will 
not believe. We must therefore recognize that tlicre is an inward cause 
which moves a man from witliin to assent to the tilings of faith/ 'God, 
who moves us inwardly by grace^. <ST ZZae^ Q- 6, a_ 1 .} Aquinas thought 
that philosophical theology- was a science whose lesults ivere demonstrably 
certain, Swinburne and I land, E daresay, mosE coniemporary philosophical 
theologians^ think its results are oniy probable. We also recognize that 
many of our epistemic peeis find our arguments unpersuasi^'e. Shouldn^t 
we conclude^ then, that people's relation to the theistic e^-ldence is veiy 
much like their reiation to miiaclei and ether external sagns in Aquinas's 
view? 

L2. See Calvinj Institi^tes, Bonk iii^ ch, ii^ nos IS-lfi. Cf_ Ai^juinas's claim that faith 
i5 'an at:E of the intehect as directed lo one object by the wiU' (ST Z2aej Q. 4, 
a_ 1>_ The intellect assents because the \\i]\ deems it good to do so. So 
Aquinas also thinks that faith involves a response to God as one's good- 
ie. The philosophers argued that the world was eternal, and that texts like Sura 
10 ('Surety your Lord is God who created heavens and the earth in six days') 
should hii interpreted in a way consistent with that fact. Given the Aris- 
totelian framework within which the phiEosophers were working, howeveij, 
eternity and necessity are coextensi^-e. So ii God eternally creates the worlds 
He necessarily creates itj and hence doesn'l freely chooive it_ A Gtsd witbout 
free will^ though^ isn't a personal agent and so isn't the God of theism- Tor 
my lemaiks on Udayana and aUGhazali I am indebted to John Clayton, 
'Retigions^ Reasons, and Gods""^ R^iif^ioits Stiuiies 23 (1987): 1-17 and Tiety 
a]iiJ the Proofs', Reli^iGiis Studies 26 n99()i: 19-42. 

14_ See, for esampie, Karl Earth. A}J:seh}]: Fiiies Qiuit^retvi inteiiecUmf (Richmond, 
VA: John Knox Press^ 196C); and Marilyn Adams,, Traying the Proslogiim\ in 
Tliomas Senor Ced_}. Ti^e Rutiofhility ^f BeHtrf and the Phiuility of Faitfi (Ithaca: 
Cornel! University Press, 1995J- 

I5_ Although It sometimes was, Tliomas's S^mfWa Conira Gefitiies Is partly 
directed towards Muslims and Anselm's Mt^imiogiot^ is addre^ed to the 
'ignorant' as well as to his fellow monks. 

1 6_ Over the nature of CSod's foreknowEedge, for example, or the Atonement. Cf_ 
The disputes between Thomists and Ockhamists over foreknowledge, or 
between Abelard and other medievaj theologians over the nature of the 

Atonement- 

•i 

17. Fences Z4Z. For f no f:^ ^j^r FasMt, _vw' my Pf!ifo^ophyofRet[i^on, 2nded_ tBriteflont^ 
CA: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1998), ch. 6. S^ alao Daniel Clifford Fouke, 
'Argument in Pascal's F^nse^s', Histor}' af Fi7sh)sopln' Quatteriy 6 (19S9|: 57-63, 

1S_ And not only for these propositions. In my view, our i"?assiona3 nature 
affects almost all cumuEative case reasoning. 

19_ Ahhough, of course, we c^in (and shouidj eliminate obvious prejudice, be 
open to new evidence and responsive to criticism, cultivate a sense of our 
o^^'n falJibilitVr and so on_ 



30 PtsUGSf?piiy ofRiiti^w}! w the 21st Century 



20. That DS-. between equally intelligent and well-informed mquirers. who are 
equipped by training to deal with the relevant issues^ and who display al3 
the standard intellectuaa \nrtuL='i; i:mtellectua3 honesty, openness to criticiiinn, 
even-handed treatment of the retevant evidence, and so onj_ 

21 . Unless I misunderstand him^ Swinburne thinks that dispositions of the heail 
are^ at bes^ only accidentalEy necessary to the success of the evidentiaJist 
project- AcctdentaUy necessary because^ in particular cases, they may ptay a 
causafc role in eliminating prejudice^ lioslaEit^r to criticism, and other stan- 
dard intellectual vices. In my view^ dispositions of the heart are essential. 

22. In my opinion, properly formed religious beliefs tjpicaliy rest on inchoate 
arguments o( some complexity tand^ in parEicular^ on i]:iterGnces to the hest 
explanationj. Usually however^ these arguments aren't carutully articulated- 
The viitue of philosophical ar^ments hke Paley's or Swinburne's is to make 
these more or 3ess inarticulate arguments explicit^ and to defend them 
against objections. My position on this issue has a certain similarity to 
Jacques Maritain's. Maritain argues that Aquinas's five ways are a 'develop- 
ment and unfolding' of a natural knowledge of God which consists of an 
intuition of beings and a 'prompt, spontaneous reasoning' that is "'more or 
tess involved in it'_ lAppnhiches to GOif {New York: Ccllier Books, 1962J, 
cli. l.i This view differs from Plantinga's, Plantinga concedes that there is 
tittfe difference between himself and those who think that theistic belief is 
the product of inferences from the glories of nature, the promptings of corv* 
science, and so on w^htm tho^e infen^rjce^ ure 'ipontti^iemx.^^ cm?\p^!Un^ ami iiir^ct 
iu the serjse of im'oivin^ few or no iiitemieitiate steps. In my view (and [ think 
also Maritain's), mature religious beliefs may be (moie or less^ spontaneous 
and compelhng- But they are 3ieit3ier properly basic icuf the result of sinapSe 
Immediate inferences of the sort Planttnga describes. On the contrary. 
A[t]iough the inferences may be implicit^ ajid ]iot fully articulate^ they 
typically involve assessments of rather complex bodies of evidence. 



3 

Voices in Discussion 

D.Z. PhiUlps 



A: Wc need Imp^Lrtial criteria by which to assess evidence for the Iruth 
of liie proposition There is a God\ This evidence needs to be spelled 
out, 1 take myself to be addressing a belief held by Christians, Jews and 
Muslims, Wc need religion to be rational 

People conic to religious belief in various ways. Sonic conic to it 
through a religious experience. Others betlevc on the authority of the 
wise men in their community^ These are perfectly natural ways of com- 
ing to iKlicve. But they are less available than they once were. There are 
conflicting authorities and many have not liad religious experiences. In 
any case^ logically prior to these is a claim that certain propositions arc 
true. How is this claim to be defended by an appeal to impartial reason? 
There are three ways of doing so. The first of these is the onlological 
argument according to which the statement There i^ no God' is self- 
contradictor};^. Since the statement Is clearly coherent this argument 
makes an inipossiblc claim. Tlie second argument is froni the world to 
Godj but one which claims to be deductive. Aquinas argues that from 
the fact that the world has certain features, it follows, deductively^ that it 
was created by God. But since it is clearly possible that the world was not 
cieatcd by God, 1 cannot see that this aigumenl works either. 1 therefore 
prefer a third kind of argument from the w^orld to God which is Infer- 
ential in character^ but which is an inductive argument, i think it is an 
argument w^hich appeals to ordinarj^ people when they are impressed 
by tlie ordinary world as a marvellous place. 

The effect of the evidence is cumulative. Various kinds of evidence 
vaiy in strength. It is not an all-or-nothing affair. Wc VhTEll be satisfied 
with a probability of more than a half. 

Let me take but one example - natural laws. Why is there such a con- 
formiLy? We must ask questions like: Would you expect a phenomenon 



31 



32 FhUosoptiy ofR^ti^w}! w the 21st Century 

such as this if Ihcrc were tio God? [f God is all powcilul wouldn't you 
expect to find order in the world? Order Is a bcEiuUful thing. 

Of course, human beings have choices. They can make bombs to 
destroy people, or grow phiils to nourish theniu Bui without order that 
very choice makes no sense. 

If there is no God you have no reason for IhinkiniT why Ihe world 
is as it is. My suggestion is that when you consider ihis question then, 
as in science, you should go for the simplest cjtplanation- 1 have made 
use of Hayes's theorem to show that probability is on the side of the thc- 
istic explanation. 1 believe this captures what ordinary people feel when 
they look at the heavens and feel that this is the 'work of a personal 
desij;neL 

Some people have said that whereas I only offer probability, faiili 
demands certainly. Such cerlainLy would Ix^ nice, but many are not so 
blessed. So in practice, less than certainty is perfectly adequate. Live on 
tlie assumption that iheism is true. 

Others have said that what 1 do is too complicated, but all 1 am doing 
is ^ving a defence of a basic faith in face of the objections of others 
against it. 



B: I am in substantial agreement with A. I think that evidcntialism is a 
good project. Its arguments are generally persuasive and formulate, in 
more precise forms, arguments w-hich ordinary believers employ So 
I do not Lhink that A is w^rong, but incomplete. Let me notc# therefore^ 
five ways in which I diverge from A. 

firsts I am sceptical about the extent to which A^s kind of argument is 
efftictivc with educated audiences today. Second^ I do not think that 
these arguments produce faith. As Aquinas, Cabin, Kierkegaard and oth- 
crs have pointed out, certainty is a feature of faith. Jonathan Edwards and 
the Puritans disLinguished between historical faith , simply believing cer- 
tain propositions atout God, and faith as a gift of grace. In this respect, I 
am more Augustinian and A is more Pelagian. Third, arguments were 
used to settle intra-mural religious disputes. This would be a case of try- 
ing to understand what is already believed. Fourth^ A does not emplia- 
size^ as Edwards did, the importance of a properly disposed heart in 
assessing evidence which is, admittedly, public. These arguments con- 
cern antecedent probabilities which enable one to demand less evi- 
dence dian one would do otherwise. 

The question of how "wc make these antecedent judgements and of 
how' they relate to the evidence is a complicated one, but it is not a new 
issue. 1 IkIicvc it is present in Plato's 'Seventh Letter' in the emphasis 



there on the Importance of character and love of justice in judgenients. 
I think it Is also involved in Aristotle's accounl of moral reasoning. The 
task is to extend these insights to other fields. These issues are clearly 
Important In historical judgements; for example, in wiiat one thinks of 
the behaviour of the Commune in Paris after tl:ie Revolution- 
Fifth, a point I did not mention in my paper There is. some sign of 
philosophers applying their analytic skills to non-theistic religions. 
These religions offer competing examples of the facts of human experi- 
ence. I believe it is incumbent on us to give the same attention lo these 
large compcLing world-views. 



C: May I^ at the opening of this first session, press A and B on their philo- 
sophical methods? They arc both happy with philosophy of religion 
having an apologetic function. They arc concerned with the truth of the 
proposition There is a GckIV But there is a contemplative tradition In 
phlloiopJiy which is concerned with the sense of things. Until we 
know^ the sense of a proposition we do not know how to go about 
assessing its truth or falsity. Bui it will be concerned with the nature of 
'truth' and what disagreements look like. I have difficulty wit It the 
accounts A and B have given of disagrcenienl between believers and 
unbelievers. A tells us that it is a difference In the assessment of proba- 
bilities. For some scientists, for example, it is probable that the law-s of 
nature testify to a designer, while for others it is not- But isn't that 
itself an improbable account of disagreement? Scientists, who trade in 
hypotheses and probabilities, who have been trained to do so, fail to 
agree about the probability of belief in God even when confronted by 
the same evidence. 

Now B has an explanation for this or^ at least, is attracted by one. The 
faculties of unbelievers aren^E working properly. Locke said something 
similar to explain ihe limitailons in oui knowledge, but iieikelcy 
responded by denying this, He said that we first throw up a dust and 
then complain we cannot see. The fault is in our own conceptual confu- 
sions. I think this of the anaEog\^ 'wUh faulty faculties. In the case of 
eyesight. It is essential that the noim of normal eyesight is agreed on. 
Thus, those who are colour-blind, or who have faulty eyesight acknowE- 
edge these defects themselves, liui this is not so in the religious context. 
The circularity in iJ^s argument shows that the analogy doesn't work_ it 
looks as tliough we are offered an explanation: people don^t believe in 
God because their faculties are not functioning properly. What do we 
mean by 'not functioning properly'? That they don^t believe. Further, B 
has to account for the fact that there have been philosophers W'ho have 



34 ffjihsGpiiy ofRiiti^kvf w the 21st Century 



seen sense in religious belief who arc fiof believers. On B's view, how is 
Ihis possible? flow do you respond to these mcihodological points? 

A: I do want to say that the unbcJte^^er is wrong. What stands in the way 
of his agreeing with the believer? Firsl^ there is an obstacle in that people 
do not like what religion asks of tlicmn the way of life it demands, and 
so they resist the probability which the evidence shows. So they aren^l 
fully rational when they do this. 

Second, as I have said, people in some societies come to believe by 
deferring to wise men. This is true of our age where people defer too 
soon to scientific opinion dtcnicd to be wise. Bui these people may be 
biased and so people are led astray in following them. 

Thifd, let us not forget that disagreement about hypotheses occurs 
wlihln science itself. Tn the case of religious belief the matter is not 
obvious and involves us in metaphysical speculation. 

B: I think we must own up to the danger of inteilectual phariseetsm, 
and be aware of the sinhilncss of our own epistemic faculties. We can 
blind ourseives to things and fall foul of self-deception « 

We must also acknowledge that in our religious critique we are going 
to appeal to mctapJiysical considerations. We must admit that we arc 
faced with a multitude of stories which interpret the facts - metaphyslca] 
world-views. Of course we have to pay attention to evidence^ but we 
wili always need lo interpret it according to sonic w^orld-view^. 

D: ] am no friend of the ontological argument, but 1 think A is too 
iiasty in his dismissal of It. Things can seem coliercnt when they arc 
not. So altliough 'There is no God' may seem coherent, it may not be. 

.4: But I thint: There is no God' is obviously coherent. 

E: Ontological arguments differ Instead of dealing with logically neces-^ 
sary truths in (he abstract, Anselm is trying to bring out certain fea- 
tures of Ihe concept of God. He starts with thai concept rather than 

arguing to a logically necessary truth. 

A: liut the concept he starts with is of a being whose existence is logi^ 
cally necessary. 

F 

F: So the God you arrive at by inferred probabilities Is a different con- 
C-eption from that of Anselm? 

A: Yes, lie lias the notion of a logically necessary being. 



uj:. i^fifitips 35 



F: I think you are leaving out the rcli^lou:^ significance of what Ansclm 
is wrestling with - 'that than which none greater can be conceived'. 
This significance has been explored by thinkers Ukc Levlnas and 
J--L- Marion, hi analytic hands, the ontological argument has become a 
shadow of its historical self- It has been divorced from its religious 
frameworL 

A: 1 don^t deny Ansclm's religious concerns. 1 aiTii objecting to the way 

he spelled them out. 

G: Af w^haL is the religious import of your project? Wc need to know 

this probability, you say, iii order for belief to be rational. It is supposed 
to helpn but ivhat does it help? 

A: Religion asks us lo live in a certain way; it demands much of us. So 
wc need reasons to think that the practice of religion is worthwhile. 
The more evidence w^c have the better. How much wt need depends on 
circumstances^ but IVe suggested tliat over fifty per cent probability is 
enough. 

G: Again, I ask: 'enough for wliat? What were believers doing l>efore 
tliey had your arguments to rely on? 

A: I didn't give them aiiy new arguments. I simply knocked the ones they 
already had into shape. 1 referred to Gregor)^ of Nyssa in this respccL 

H: I w-ant to ask the same question as G. Anselm is explicating a faitli he 
had already. And your last response to (j might suggest a similar posi- 
tion. But your project makes a far stronger claim, It purports to start 
from a neutral starling-point. 

A: Where you start depends on the times and the state of the people. 

f: One of the differences in our time is the plurality of plausibility- 
structures. So (Kople [lave searched for a critical and evaluative science. 
How is that going to come from the analytic context? 

■ ^ 

/l For example, how is A's appeal to simplicity supposed to work? 

K: And even if the probability of a first cause is established, what would 
tliat have to do with religion? 

B: 1 don^t think it is just an appeal to simplicit)*^ / is right to question that. 
In large-scale metaphorical disputes criteria only work for those who hold 
tliG metaphysical \riew in question, i confess to not being so interested in 
the plausibility stnjctures that I refers to^ but I am interested in f s point 



^6 I^hUosGpiiy ofR^ti^w}! w the 21st Century 

about the rctation of w^orld-vicws or iiitcrprctatLons to the facts of 
human cxistcncc. 

L: Thai is an issue which can be raised In connccUon with all sorts of 

reasoning, not simply religion. Sensitivity^ to context is important 

M: In tliat connection, I don't think Aquinas was so much concerned 
Willi proofs as with a theological science where first principles can be 
used as principles of interpretation. 

A: I certainly do not want to deny the importance of sensitivity. It is an 
essential factor in being led in one direction by the data and not 
olliers; for example^ in being led to Ciiristianity and not to some other 
retlj^ion. On the other hand, despite tlie importance of contexts, remem- 
ber that the one ] appeal to is uni^^ersal - our involvcinent in llie uni- 
verse and the desire to know how it came abotit. 



H: But could a believer be atlieistic with respect to theism? 
A: I don't see how he couid. 



Ti; 



Cr I think lie means ""atheistic' tn the sense of denying the methods of 
philosophical theism. 

A: As I have said^ you can believe on the basis of authority. But in the 
absence of authority, or faced by conflicting autliorities, we must have 
reasons for embracing religious belief. 

The point of religion is getting right with God. But this would have 
no point if you did not believe that there is a God. You could have that 
belief without any religious practice, but, nevertheless, in answer to K, 
I do belicvT that that belief in God as a first cause is the same as that 
held by ordinary believers in their religious practice. 



Part II 

Reformed Episteinology 



4 

Reformed Epistemology 



The assigned task of Professor Wykstra and nfiyself is to state what we 
regard as the most serious objections to Reformed Epistemology^ and 
then to assess whcUierr In our judgement, those objections have been 
adequately met It is our Judscmentn however, that so m^in^ objections 
to Reformed Epistemology have been based on misunderstanding that 
it IS necessary, before we take up the assigned task, to explain what 
Reformed Epistemology is. Accordingly, our papers will not take the 
form of presentation and response but lather the form of Joint presen- 
tation: I will deal mainly with the nature of Reformed Epistemology^ 
although along the way I w-ill deal with certain objections, and Professor 
Wykstjra ivill deal mainly with objections^ although along the way he 
will say something about the nature. 

One might articulate the natuie of Reformed Epistemology in purely 
systematic fashion. On this occasion 1 instead propose doing so within 
a narrative contcjct. 1 have rather often been asked what led to the 
emergence of Reformed Epistcmologj' I propose interweaving an artic- 
ulation of the nature of Reformed Epistemology with a narrative of 
its origins. Historians have a big advantage over philosophers in that^ 
whereas they ahvays tiave stories to tctl^ philosoptiers only now 
and then can tell stories. People love stones. Best then for philoso- 
phers to tell stories when they can. LJut my reason for interweavmg 
narrative with analysis is not just that this will add spice to the 
discussion. 1 think one understands better ihe nature of (teformed 
Epistemolo^ if one aho understands its significance- and the best way 
to understand its significance is within the context of an account of its 
origins. Accotdinj^ly, 1 propose introducing my discussion with an 
account of the origins, the nature, and the significance of Reformed 
Epistemology. 



39 



40 FtsUGSf?piiy ofRiiti^w}! w the 21st Cetitury 



Reformed Epistcniology made its full appearance on the philosophical 
scene wilh the publication In 198^ of the collection Ftiitii ami RutioniUity, 
subtitled Reasori {imi Hetief'as God, edited by AlvLn PlanKnjja and myself J 
For a good many years Plantinga and 1 had l>ecn teaching togclher in 
the philosophy department at Calvin College. We had known each othet 
since the time when we were students together at Calvin, in the early 
1950s. Around the mid-JOs, Calvin began what it called The Calvin 
Center for Christian Scholarship. The Center continues to this day; and 
has by now acquired a very disttnj^uishcd historj^ in the promotion of 
Christian scholarship. In its early years, the principal activity of the 
Center consisted of adopting a topic for study each year, and then 
assembling a team composed of a few Calvin faculty members^ along 
with a few faculty members from other institutions, to spend the year 
working on tlie topic, free of leaching responsibilities. Each year a few 
Calvin students were also part of the team. 

The topic for the year 1979-SO was Toward a Rcforaned View of Faith 
and Reason'- Senior fellows for the year who were drawn from the Cahin 
faculty included Plantinga and myself (along with George Marsden from 
history, Robert Manw-cilcr from physics, and David liolwerda from hib- 
Meal studies). During the second semester, George Mavrode^^ from the 
University of Michigan, joined us as a senior fellow. And throughout 
tlic year, William 1^. Alston^ itien al the University of Illinois, and tlcnk 
Hait^ from the Institute of Christian Studies in Toronto, "were adjunct 
senior fellows who rather frequently dropped hi for discussions. The 
volume, Fmtii mid R^itionaflt}', emerged from the 'work of Ihe fellows 
during tliat year^ 

Above, T described the publication of Faitlt and Rtitloimlity as marking 
the 'full appearance' of Reformed tpistemology on the philosophical 
scene, I meant thereby to suggest that earlier there had been an appear- 
ance which was somewhat less than full. Or to put it in terms of 
'stages': the publication of Faith ami RntiomiliPi' consiiUitcd the second 
stage in the development of Reformed Epistemology. The first stage 
jcame In two parts. One part consisted of some essays published by 
PlanLinga in the late 1970s and early HCs - in particularn 'Is Belief 
in God Properly Basic?'- The other consisted of a small book of mine, 
Reason within the lk}timis of lieiigion, published in 1976/'^ 

Behind each of these there Avas, in turn, a pre-histoTy_ The pre-htstor^r 
of Plantiiiga'scssayj 'Is Belief in God Properly Basic?' was his 1967 book, 
God and Otiier !^iimh, subtitled, A Study of the Ratiomil Jta^tipcation of 
Belief in GoiL^ The pre-hlstory of my own bbook, Reasoii within tlie Bounds 
ofRefis;ion, was an essay published in 1964, Taith and Phtlosophy*/ 



Nichofds WGiter.^tojff^ 41 



Why do I say that these belong to the 'pre history' of Reformed Epistc- 
molog}^, rather than tliaL they consiitute the first stage in its history 
proper? Essential to Reformed Epistomoto^ 15 the explicit refection of 
classical fouiidationaiisnij and of the cvidciiliattsl ohjection to religious 
belief (realistically understood) which is implied by classical foundation- 
alism- Uut in Planliiiga^s book Gmi d!hf Ctfwr Mlmis, and in my essay 
Taith and l^hilosophy'^ there was no explicit recognition of classical 
foundationalisin, and hence no explicit rejection of it. Neither PlantiiiKa 
nor I had yet identified classical foundationalism as SLich; neither of us 
had ycL formed the concept. 

In that regard, v\t vv^ere not unusuaL It was only later that mcta- 
cpistemology became a mailer of serious interest to philosophers; and 
only when it did become a matter of serious intercsi, sometime in the 
70s, was classical foundationalism identified as one distinct style of 
cpTstemoIog)^ Of course, classical foundationalism itself had been around 
for centuries; what was absent, until the 1970s, was a clear Fecognltion 
of its nature, and a clear recognition of the fact that it was but one of 
many options for epislemological theory. 

It was the emergence of meta-cpistemology, and the coitceptiializing of 
classical foundationalism which accompanied that emergence - indeed, 
which that emergence made possible - it was that emergence and that 
concept ualizing wh ich made Re formed Epistemolog)^ possible . The 
explicit use of the concept of classical foundationalism (sometimes just 
called 'foundationalism""} is whal separates the first stage in the dcv'i?l- 
opment of Reformed Epistemologj^^ from its prc-history. 

To say that the first stage of lieformed Epistemology had a pre- 
history in some earlier writings of Plantinga and myself is of course to 
suggest some sort of continuity between the pre-history and the first 
stage, fl should state here, lest there be any misunderstanding, that there 
Ls In turn a long pre-hisLoiy behind those early writings of Platiiinga 
and myselTl What was that continuity? When a clear reco^ition of 
classical foundationalLsmn for what it is, appeared on the philosophical 
scene, by no means did everybody thinking about the epistemolo^ of 
religious belief immediately become a Reformed Epistcmologist. Why 
then did Reformed Epistemology emerge wliere it did? 

Plantinga and 1, from the time of our student days at Calvin College^ 
had been profoundly shaped by a movement within the Reformed- 
Presbyterian tradition of Cliristianity; namely, the Dutch neo-Calvinist 
movement of the late nineteenth century, of which the great formative 
figure was the Dutch theologian, journalist, and statesman, Abraham 
Kuypcr Our most influential college teachers were all 'Kuypcrians'. 



42 FhUDSf?piiy ofR^ti^w}! w the 21st Century 



Faith seekmg urjderstamfmg was Ehc motlo held up before us as guide 
and challenge for the Christian IntcllcctuaV The motto comes of course 
from Augustine, who in turn took it from Clement of Alexandria. 
1 now know that the way we were taughE to understand it was not, 
howevei^ the way Augustine meant It. What Augustine meant was that 
the Christian intellectual seeks to understand those very things that 
already he or she believes. What we were taught to understand by the 
motto is that it is the calling of the Christian intellectual to conduct all 
of his or hcf inquiries in the light of fahh. ^Jot to move from befU'viug, 
saVp the doctrine of divine simplicUyj to iimierstiuuling that vciy same 
doctrine - that would fit the Augustlnlan understanding of the motto - 
but to develop history, sociolog}^, philosophy, political thcorVr and so 
forth, in the light of faith. 

A striking feature of this way of seeing the challenge facing the 
Christian scholar and intellectual is that nothing at all is said about the 
need to develop arguments for one's religious beliefs. The discussions 
concerning faith and reason which have preoccupied the church down 
through the centuries can pretty much all be classified as either discus- 
sions concerning the proper role of reason in faith or as discussions con- 
cerning the proper role of faith in one's reasoning. In the fMtch 
neo-Calvinist tradition^ the attention was all on the latter. But that^ of 
course, Implied something concerning the former. To urge that faith seek 
understanding, while paying no attention at all to arguments for the 
existence of God^ to arguments for the reliability of Scripture, and so 
forth, was to take for granted that the evidentialist challenge to religious 
belief (more about this shortly) does not have to be met- It was 
to take for granted that the fundamentals of faith do not typically need 
the support of reasoning, ol argumentatioiij for faith to l>c acceptable- 
PlantingSj in his essay in Fiuth nf^d Ratio!fa{it}\ cites passages from the 
Dutch neo-Calvinist theologian Herman tiaviiick which say exactly that- 

In short, it would only be a slight exaggeration to say that Reformed 
Epistcmology is a development that was destined to occur among 
philosophers within the neo-Calvinist tradition once the concept of 
^classical foundationalism l>ccamc clearly articulated. 

So what then is Reformed Epistemolog)^? It will be helpful to distin- 
guish between Reformed Episteniolog)'jitfafm;v^|^ iimkrsttmd, and Reformed 
fepistemolog>' broadly understood. Let me here describe the former; later 
1 will explain what I have in mind by 'Reformed Epistemolog)' broadly 
understood'. A preliminary' observation Is iit order Beliefs have a number 
of distinct truth-relevant merits: warranted, reliably formed, kno^^i^, 
entitled, apt for inclusion in science^ and so forth. Until rather recently, 



Nicholas Woitpr^toiff^ 4:i 



twentieth century cpistcmology in the analytic tradition was con- 

duclcd as if there were jusi two truih-rclcviint merits: justification, or 
rationality^ plus knowledge^ this tatter being understood as what 
resulted when one added tiutli to a justifiably or EaLiociaily held belief 
(alternatively: what resulted when one added truth plus some Gettier- 
coping property). The main disputes were understood as being disputes 
concerning the correct analysis of justification, or rationatity Though T 
won't l:kerc take time to argue Lhe point, the situation seems to ine 
clearly Instead to. be that philosopiicrs liave implicitly tKen discussing a 
number of disliaicl^ tliougli related^ merits. The relevance of this point 
concerning the inultlpHclt>' of doxastic merits for our purposes here is 
tliatj strictly speakings we ought not to speak of Reformed Epistemology 
tout cmstt^ but of Reformed Epistemolog}^ concerning warrant, of 
Reformed lLpistemolog\^ concerning entitlement, and so on. At the 
beginnings however^ tliis pointy about the plurality of doxastic merits^ 
was not recognized; Reformed cpistcmologlsts spoke almost exclusively 
about rationalitv. 

I can now explain what I take Reformed Epistemology^ narrowly 
understood, to be. In tlic linlightenment ttiere emerged the ideal of a 
ratiomiUy groun^icd religion, tlie two great proponents of this ideal l:^cing 
John Locke and Immanuel Kant. Religion as it comcs^ so it was said, is 
not satisfactory; what it lacks is rational grounding. In LockCj it's clear 
that tfie imiivhiiiiif believer is regarded as believing itn^sponsibly unless 
his religious beliefs are all rationally grounded; in Kant^ it remains 
unclear how exactly the individual believer must be related to the ideal 
of rational grounding. 

Reformed epistemology is the repudiation of this Enlightenment 
ideal of rationally grounded religion. Let it be said as emphatically as 
possible that Reformed epistemologists did not repudiate the demands 
of lationality (and now, after tlie recognition of tlie diversity of doxastic 
merits, do not repudiate the w^orth and the demands of warrant, entitle- 
mentn and so on). What they repudiated was the claim thatj for a per- 
son's religious beliefs to be rational - in particular, for their beliefs about 
God to be rational - those beliefs must in their totality be rationally 
grounded. Ratiofmlfty i.s \wt to bt eijuated with ratiomjl groiifhUfig. The 
way the Reformed epistemologists made this point was to insist that 
some religious beliefs arc rational even though they are held himfedi" 
ately. To say that a person holds some belief hnmndiateiy is to say that 
the belief is not held on the basis of other propositions that the person 
believes, those oilier propositions functioning then as reasons for the 
person's beliefs. 



44 fhiiGsopiiy ofR^ti^kvi w the 21st Century 



Notice thai Reformed Epistcniology docs not say Lhat c^^ciy immediate 

belief about God held by anybody whalsocvej; possesses the meril 
under consideration. The claim is tlic much more guarded claim tliat 
soffie of the immediate beliefs about God held by some persons possess 
that merit. In fact the Reformed Epistemologist is of the view that foi 
every doxastic merit, there will surely be some persons who hold some 
immediate beliefs about God which lack that merit, [n some such 
cases, the person will have iiefaiten for the belief- lhat is to say: there 
will be something in the person or the person^s situation such that, 
given that factor or situation, if the person were functioning properly, 
he or she would not hold that belief immediately. The defeater, in 
some caseSe will be a belief of the person which is a reason against the 
belief about God in question. Thus, contrary to what has sometimes 
been said, Reformed Lpistcmolo^y is most certainly not a species of 
religious dogmatism. 

Furthermore, the character or situation of many persons Is no doubt 
such thai for some proposition about God and some doxastic merit, 
their belief of that proposition could not possess the merit in question 
without being held for (goodl teasons. For some doxastic merits and 
some propositions about God it may even be the case lhat no one could 
belie^^e those propositions immediately and their belief possess that 
merit. And even when a person's immediate belief about God possesses 
the merit in question, the Reformed Epistcmolojjist will normally not 
see anything wrong in the person also holding that belief for reasons. 
Reformed Hpistemology is most definitely not opposed to offering 
reasons for one's religious beliefs. The Reformed lipistemologist is not 
even opposed to all forms of ivhat might be called ^natural theology'. 
But if someone claims that natural theological arguments arc m'ces.'^aiy 
for any belief in God to possess some doxastic merit or othcr^ then the 
suspicions of the Reformed episicmologist w^ill be ineluciably aroused. 

Be it noted thai Reformed Epistemolo^^ narrowly understood, is an 
epistcmological claim - as indeed the name suggests. Iteformed Episte-^ 
molog)' has sometimes been criticized for its failure to give an account of 
the nature of religious belief and of the role of religious beliefs In our 
lives- AlternativeJy, it has sometimes been understood as aiming to give 
such an account and then been criticized for giving a woefully inade- 
quate account. One flnd^ this fatter criticism (perhaps also the former) in 
D.Z. Phillips^s bookj Faith afier FouiidatsotialisitL^ How much more 
adequate, exclaims Phillips^ Is the account of the role in life of religious 
languai^e and belief which is to be found in Wittgenstein and his 
followers. The 'elucidation of religious concepts^ E^^'I^S ^ perspicuous 



Nichofds Woitpr^toiff^ 45 



representation of them in their natural contejcts^ is neglected in favour 
of Uic slark assertion of a l^cllcver's right to place belief in God among 
hi5 foundational beliefs/ says Phillips.^ 

[Jut Reformed Episteniology- and it makes no difference now whether 

we understand it narrowEy or broadly - Reformed Epistemolog>^ never 
intended to be anj^hing other than epistcmologj^. It never aimed at 
giivEng an account of the nature of religious language and belief; it never 
aimed at describing the role of religious language and belief in the life of 
tlie reUgtous person. It is, and always intended to be, a contribution to 
cpisLcmology. (Though in many places one finds Reformed epislcmolo- 
gists making remarks about role - for example, in my introduction to 
Faith imd PhUuso{?hy. J 

The mention of Phillips's Faith {ifi<cr Foimdntiofmlism leads me to 
mention another, connected^ misunderstanding which inhabits the 
first part of that book. In stating the core thesis of Reformed Episteniol- 
ogy, narrowly understood^ 1 spoke of a belief which a person holds 
lmmediatef}\ Call such a belief, an hmnedhite belief. Plantinga, by contrast^ 
lias usually used the term 'basic beliefj rather than 'immediate belief. 
And whereas I have said that we must distinguish between Reformed 
Epistemology concerning warrant, Reformed Epistcniology^ concerning 
entitlement. Reformed Epistemology concerning aptness for theorv^ and 
so forth, Plantinga has typically used the catch-all word, 'properl^^. Thus 
Plantinga has typically conducted the discussion in terms of what he calls 
■"properly baste' beliefs. (He has also sometimes spoken of 'taking^ beliefs 
to be properly basics when all he means - contrary^ to what a good many 
commentators have supposed - is that they are properly basic.) 

By 'basic belief Plantinga means the very same as what I mean by 
'immediate belief. The term 'basic' has certain connotations, however, 
which the term 'immediate' does not have? and those connotations 
have led to two all-too-typlcal misunderstandings. In the first place^ the 
term 'basic' suggests that the religious beliefs in question serve as the 
basiSj that is^ the foundation^ for one^s structure of warranted religious 
hellcfs, for one's structure of entitled religious heltefs, or whatever. And 
that has led a good many commentators to claim that the polemic of 
Reformed Epistemology against classical foundattonalism is misleading. 
Reformed Epislemology is opposed, indeed, lo dassicd toundationalism. 
But it^s not opposed, so it is said, to foiwdationuiism as such_ It's just 
another version of foundationalism^ a version somewhat more gcncmus 
as to what it allows in the foundations than is classical foundationalism. 
All in all, thcn^ so it is said, there is much less here than meets the eye.^ 
But this is all a misunderstanding- Reformed Epistemology, narrowly 



46 fhUo.wpiiy ofRiiti^w}! w f/re 21st Century 



uiidcrsEood, docs not commit those who embrace this thesis lo 
any form of fouiidEiUoiialisni whatsoever. To acknowledge thai some 
beliefs are held immediately, and to acknowledge that some of those 
which arc held immediately possess the doxastic merit in question - 
(hat even some immediately held beliefs about God possess the mcril 
in queslion - does not commit one to foundationalism of any sort. 
A cohercnlist could sav as much. Alt foundationalists do in fact make 
(he mediate/immediate disiLnctioii. But they are not foundationalists 
just by viiiue of nnaking the distinction; they arc foundationalists by 
virtue of what they do wi(h the dislinction in articulating their cpiste- 
mologies. Til explain these somewhat dark sayings shortly, when 1 
argue that the positive cpistemologies which the Reformed cpistemolo- 
gists have developed in the third stage of Reformed Epistemology have 
in fact not been fo Linda tlonali si in their basic structure. The thesis of 
Refornied Epistemolog)^ narrowly understood, though it did no( com- 
mil the Reformed Epislemologlst to foundationalism, did indeed leave 
open that possibility^ the Reformed epistemologists have not, in fact, 
fexploilcd that opening- 

In the comparison \ify DZ. Phillips of Reformed Epistcmolog>^ 
to VVittgei:istein's pliilosopiiy of religion, tn chapter 4 of Faith af^t^r Fomi' 
diitiofhilisffi, one finds an additional misunderstanding of what 
the Reformed Epistemologisl has in mind by 'basic beliefs'. Phillips 
assumes there tliat the Reformed epistcmologist has his eye on the same 
thing that Wittgenstein has his eye on in On Ceftuifityf when Wittgen- 
stein talks about those he!ie£s that are certain for us because they are 
^held fast' by all Ihat surrounds them. Given the assumption thai the 
^ame thing is under cons] deration^ Phillips then criticises Reformed Epis- 
icmologj' for thinking of religious beliefs in such an atomistic fashion. 

But I submit that the topics here arc just different; 'basic tKlief' is 
being used ambiguously The plicnomenon on which Wittgenstein had 
his eye is that wliich Plantinga. in his essay in FaitJi ami R^thuatity, 
calls ■'depth of ingrcssion\ Certain heliefs arc so deeply ingrcssed 
within one's belief-structure that to give them up would require giving 
up a vast number of other beliefs as welh The difficulty of doing that is^ 
then^ what holds them fast. My belief that the world began quite some 
lime ago is one example of a deeply ingrcssed belief. So too^ as one of 
Wittgenstein's examples suggests, is my belief that my name is 
'Nicholas Woltcrstorff . 

Not only is the distinction between deep and shallow ingressioh just 
a different distinctioi:^ from that between immediate and mediate 
beliefs; there isn't even any coincidence between thcni. Some Lmmcdiate 



Nichofds Woit^rstojff^ 47 



beliefs arc deeply ingrcsscd; some arc very shallowly Ingressed. [ndecd^ 
It's even a distortion of Wittgenstein's thought to fotniulale It in tcjms 
nf beiief^. What Wittgi^nstein wa? pointing to is what wc all take for 
gnintt'd in so fundamental a way thai, were wc no longer to take it for 
granted^ we would have to alter vast stretches of our beliefs und pmc- 
tkes. Some of w^hal wc thus take for granted will he things Iwilevt'd by 
us; but much of it will never have been taken notice of sufficiently to 
be believed. To what extent these ideas can be used to illuminate reli- 
gious beliefs is an interesting question; I myself think that religious 
beliefs are different in fundamental ways from the deeply ingressed^ 
unshakcable beliefs to which Wittgenstein calls attention in On Cer- 
tiunt}\ Uut ill any case^ what Wittgenstein is discussing is simply differ- 
ent from what the Reformed Epistemologist is talking about when he 
speaks of basic, that is, immediate, beliefs. 

But why, thcnj does the Reformed epistemologist talk about what he 
does talk about? Why all the flurry about immediately held beliefs about 
God, and whether they can possess the dojiiastie merit in question? Why, 
more generally, the preoccupation with epistemology^? Why^ in short, 
doesn't the Reformed epistemologist act like a good Wittgensteinian and 
talk about the role of religious language and belief in life? 

The answer is that the polemical partner of Reformed Epistcmologyn 
narrowly understood, is not the same as the polemical partner of 
Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion; and that the character of both 
of these is in good measure shaped by their polemical partners and by 
how they have chosen to deal with those partners. In each case, absent 
know^ledge of the polemical partner^ the significance of the movement 
is in good measure lost ori one. 

The polemical partner of Wittgenstein, in his reflections on religion, 
was logical positivism. In his reflections on religion, \"\^ittgenstein chose 
not to challenge positivism's criterion of cognitive mcaiiingfuJncss head 
on, nor its principle of demarcation bet^veen science and 'metaphysics' 
wliich made use of that criterion. Instead, he undertook to exploit a 
concession which the later positlvists had themselves already made^ 
namely, the concession that meaningful speech is not confmed to fact- 
stating speech- The challenge to which Wittgenstein addressed himself^ 
In his reflections on religion, was then to describe the 'meaningfulness' 
of religious language - given that, so he assumed. It does not serve to 
state facts, tliat is^ to make true-false claims. How does religious lan- 
guage function - given that, so he assumed, it cannot be contradicted, 
since nothing is said to which one can properly say, 'Tliat's false/ 
Wittgenstein's way of dealing with his polemical partner reijuired that 



48 I^hUosoptiy ofR^ti^kvf w the 21st Century 



he discuss the role of religious lanj^agc and belief in life. There was no 
other way to make his polemical point. 

By the time Reformed Epistemolo^^ came on the scene, !o^cal posi- 
tivism was dead and buried. It wasnl yet dead and buried at the time of 
the pre-hlstory of Reformed Eplstemology; Plantinga docs battle with it 
at several points m God luui Otiici' K^huh. But by the l9S0s it was dead -at 
kast among philosophers. What was not dead and buried was a chal- 
lenge to religious belief of considerably greater antiquity than the posl- 
livist claim that religious language lacks meaning - viz.^ the challenge 
of which I :^pokc earlier^ that religious beliefs, to be held rationally, 
must in their totality be rationally grounded. Reformed epislemologists 
have ty)7ically called it the evidenti^iiist chuik'ngt^. From the insistence 
that rcUgious belief is lacking in rationality warrant, entitlement^ or 
whatever, if it is not held on good evidence, it just follow-s that it is 
lacking in those merits if it is held Lmmediatcly. This evidentialist 
challenge has been so widely held among the [ntelligenisia of the mod- 
em world that it deserves to be regarded as part of the modern mind, 
in response to the challenge, many have offered arguments for their 
own full-blown religious betlefSp others have trimmed their religious 
beliefs until they no longer go beyond what they judge the arguments 
to support; yet others have contended that the arguments are so weak 
(hat religious belief ought to be trimmed to tlie point of disappearance. 
One way or the other^ they have accepted the kgittmacy of the chal- 
lenge. The Reformed cpistemologlst, as I observed earlier^ rejects the 
challenge. In so doing he is, i suppose, a 'postmodernist' of a sort. What 
made ''postmodernism^ of his sort seem plausible to him^ however, w^as 
not immersion in the writings of Hetdeggcff, Derrlda^ and their ilk^ but 
the 'postcnodernism'' which was implicit all alon^ in the neo-Calvinist 
movement which he emhraced. 

What emerges from the foregoing is thai Reformed Eplsteniolog)'' 
and Wittgensletnian philosophy of religion have in good measure just 
^been doing different things? there is no reason why each cannot regard 
the other as having hnportant insights wliich ought to he incorporated 
within a larger picture. It appears to me that on one absolutely central 
potnc^ however, tliese two movements arc in conflict. I understand 
Wittgenstein and most of his followers - O.K. Bouwsma being the signal 
exception - to hold titat there is no such phenomenon as referring to 
God and predicating things of that to which one has referred. Religious 
language functions very^ much like the language of one's atheist friend 
w^hen he exclaims, 'Thank God it's Ftiday/ The Reformed epistemologist, 
by contrast, holds that we can and do refer to God, and predicate things 



Nichofds WGiter^toiff^ 49 



of that to which wc have referred. He furthermore holds thai these asser- 
tions about God arc either true or false of God, and that ihcy arc true or 
false of God because of the fact's of the matter. I Jud^e ttiis to be the 
decisive issue separating Reformed Eplstemology from Wittgcnstoinian 
philosophy of religion (Bouwsma excepted). I shall say a bit about the 
issue at the close of my discussion. 

I suggested that what distinguished the first stage of Reformed 
Epistemology from its pre-hisiory was the explicit use of the concepts 
of dnssic{if ^imdatiomiiism nfid evi(i£}ftinlht cimflenge. What, in turn, 
distinguishes Mie second stage from (lie first es, of course^ the greater 
elaboration and articulation of ideas hinted at in the frrst stage. But 
something else as well. Iii the year wc spent together in the Calvin 
Center for Christian Scholarship, Planlinga and I read Thomas Reid for 
the first time in our hves. For me (and for Plantinga as well, I thltikK it 
was the exhilarating experience of discovering a philosophical soul- 
mate. What w^as it that 1 (we) found in Rcid? Tve never been able fully 
to say - fully to articulate the grounds of the excitement I felt. Some- 
tliing about the experience has always eluded me. But I know some of 
what made me feel 1 had discovered a philosophical soul-male. 

Reid was not only the first articulate opponent of classical founda- 
tionalism in the history of Western philosophy; he was, at the same 
time, a metaphysical realist. That's part of what captivated me; for this 
was exactly the combiiiation, reiilf!^m plus nuti-dtissfcaJ-foiuuintiomiihin, 
wliich I had myself been trying to work out. What also captivated nic 
was the articulate picture of the human being as having a number of 
distinct belief-forming faculties^ of dispositions^ and of these faculties 
as being innocent until proved guilty. In his attack on the sceptic, Reid 
argues powerfully that, in the nature of ihe case, suspicion^ whatever 
Us relevance^ cannot be one's fundamental stance toward one's belief- 
forming faculties. But neither can one give a non^ircular defence of 
the rcliabihty of one's faculties. Tntst musl be one's fundamental 
stance. The neo-Calvinist version of the Augustinian tradition in which 
I had been reared, with Its motto of ftutli seekiiig uuderstunding and Its 
tacit repudiation of cvidentialist apologetics^ had also made trust fun- 
damental. So I10 doubt what also led me to sense in Rcid a philosophi- 
cal soul-mate was Lhc fundamental role of trust in his tliought. 
Admittedly the trust occurs at a somewhat different point, and has a 
somewhat different object; nonetheless, in both cases, human exis- 
tence is seen as resiing not on proof but ttust. 

The center of lletd's thought Avas his polemic against the explanation 
of perception offered by his predecessors, whom Rcid lumped together 



50 FtsUGSf?piiy ofRiiti^w}! w the 21st Century 



as theorists of what he called The Way of Ideas', and his articulation of 
an alternative- The Way of Ideas theorists lield that in perceplion wc 
form beliefs about our sensations, and Mien draw rational iiiferpnces 
from the propositional content of those beliefs^ Eo propositions about 
the external world. Reid polcmicized powerfully and relentlessly 
against that account; what he put in its place was the claim that 
though sensations are indeed evoked by the impact of the external 
world on us in perception, those sensations imiwdh^tdy evoke in us 
conceptions and beliefs about the external world- The move, from sen- 
sations to perceptual beliefs, is not hy virtue of some rational inference 
but by virtue of our ^hard wiring'. Ferc£ptio!i is Fiot n}tiouaf!y s^t^^^^fdedl 

What this picture of perception suggested to Plantinga and myself 
was a way of articulating John Calvin^s suggestion that all humanity is 
naturally religious. Belief in God, so Cal\4n insisted, is not an inven- 
tion; on the contrary, we are so created that, if we functioned as we 
were designed lo function, wc ivould all respond to one and another 
aspect of the 'desig'n' of the w^orld by immediate beliefs about God. 
One cannot understand Reformed Epistemolog)', as it lias been devel- 
oped, without discerning its commitment to an anthropology' of 
religion of this Calviniitic sort: all htjmanily is naturally thcisttcally 
religious. What accounts for the fact that not all human bein^ do in 
fact believe in God is that our indigenous proclivity for fotmLtig imme- 
ili^te beliefs about God has been overlaid by our fallcnness. We no 
longer function as we were created to function. 

Reformed Epistemolo^^ through its first two stages, was above all 
a brush- clearing operation, designed to dispose of the evidcnlialist 
challenge to tlicistic belief and of the classical foundational ism which 
has typically motivated tlie evidentialist challenge. The third stage of 
Reformed Epistemology, represented by work done since Faitif niui 
iUitionaiit}-', is differeniialed from the second stage by the near-absence 
of any further ground -de a ring and, in its place, the elaborate articula- 
tion of positive epistemological accounts which were only hinted at in 
Faith ami Ratiomilit}^. Wliat I mean by Reformed Epistemology broadly 
understood is those developments in the epistemology of religious belief 
which have occupied the space cleared out by Reformed Epistemology 
in its earlier negative phase^ this being what 1 have had in mind by 
Reformed rpistemolog)'^ f?rtrjwiv/y tmderstood. 

These bioader developments have come in two areas which it is 
important to distinguish- For one thing, positive cpistemologies of a 
Reformcd-epistemological sort have been developed. Some of this was 



Nichofds WGiter.^tojff^ 51 



present already in the second stagc^ represented by Faith mhi Rationality; 
but thai was onlv a foretaste of whai has come forth since then. 1 have 
m mind, in particularn William Alston's account of religious experience 
and the fustification it lends to religious beliers in his Ferceivu^ God; 
Plantinga's account of warrant In his three volumes, l1/jmiJi£ f/jp Cur- 
rent Dt'Lmte, Wifrrafxt as Proper Function, and Warranted Christian Belief,^ 
and my own account of entitlement in my Divine Dlscourse^^ and^ 
much tnore elaborately, in my forthcoming, WorUiy Mlml, atut Entitle 
inent to Believe. 

Secondiy, a considerable number of writings have appeared dealing 
with the relevance of faith to theoretical actlvit^:^. Admittedly it stretches 
the word 'epistemology^ to call these discussions, ^examples of episte- 
mology'; stricliy^ they belong to Wissenschafislelfre. Yet they have been 
so intimately connected with the more strictly epistemological develop- 
ments of Reformed Fpistcmolog^^ that it would give a mistaken impres- 
sion not to include them under tlie rubric of 'Reformed Cpistemologj^. 

^Jot much of this Reformed Wlssenschaftslehre found its way into 
Faltii and Ratioiuillt)'; epLstemolog\^ proper proved so fascinating during 
the year which gave rise to this volume tliat it pretty much blocked out 
reflections on the relevance of faith to theory. But such reflections were 
present already in what I called the ^first staged In my book Reason 
within tiie Bowuis ofH.tfJi^s:;itw. And tliey have appeared with fair regular- 
ity m the third stage; for example^ in Plantinga^s inaugural address at 
Notre Dame, ^Advice to Christian l^htlosophers^ in George Marsdcn's 
recent, The Outrageous Mea of Christum Scholarship,^^ and in various 
essays of my own- 

1 mentioned earlier that the positive accounts of doxastic merits devel- 
oped hy Reformed epistemotogists in this third sta^e have been non- 
foundation a! ist in their basic structure. Let me now explain this claim. 

The cognitive-psychological distinction between mediate and imnicdU 
ate beliefs is one which, so it seems to me, everj^one must acknowledge. 
Surely we ah have L^eliefs which we have come to hold because wc have 
inferred them from other beliefs of ours. But inference cannot be the 
sole mode of belief-formation. There must be some processes other 
than inference that produce beliefs in us; otherwise inference would 
have nothing to do its work on. Those will be processes that produce 
beliefs immediately. 

What disLinguishes the foundationalist from his fellow epistemolo- 
gists is that he articulates his account of the presence and absents 
of whatever mi^ht be the doxastic merit on which he has his eye in the 



Nichofds WGiter.^tojff^ 51 



present already in the second stagc^ represented by Faith mhi Rationality; 
but thai was onlv a foretaste of whai has come forth since then. 1 have 
m mind, in particularn William Alston's account of religious experience 
and the fustification it lends to religious beliers in his Ferceivu^ God; 
Plantinga's account of warrant In his three volumes, l1/jmiJi£ f/jp Cur- 
rent Dt'Lmte, Wifrrafxt as Proper Function, and Warranted Christian Belief,^ 
and my own account of entitlement in my Divine Dlscourse^^ and^ 
much tnore elaborately, in my forthcoming, WorUiy Mlml, atut Entitle 
inent to Believe. 

Secondiy, a considerable number of writings have appeared dealing 
with the relevance of faith to theoretical actlvit^:^. Admittedly it stretches 
the word 'epistemology^ to call these discussions, ^examples of episte- 
mology'; stricliy^ they belong to Wissenschafislelfre. Yet they have been 
so intimately connected with the more strictly epistemological develop- 
ments of Reformed Fpistcmolog^^ that it would give a mistaken impres- 
sion not to include them under tlie rubric of 'Reformed Cpistemologj^. 

^Jot much of this Reformed Wlssenschaftslehre found its way into 
Faltii and Ratioiuillt)'; epLstemolog\^ proper proved so fascinating during 
the year which gave rise to this volume tliat it pretty much blocked out 
reflections on the relevance of faith to theory. But such reflections were 
present already in what I called the ^first staged In my book Reason 
within tiie Bowuis ofH.tfJi^s:;itw. And tliey have appeared with fair regular- 
ity m the third stage; for example^ in Plantinga^s inaugural address at 
Notre Dame, ^Advice to Christian l^htlosophers^ in George Marsdcn's 
recent, The Outrageous Mea of Christum Scholarship,^^ and in various 
essays of my own- 

1 mentioned earlier that the positive accounts of doxastic merits devel- 
oped hy Reformed epistemotogists in this third sta^e have been non- 
foundation a! ist in their basic structure. Let me now explain this claim. 

The cognitive-psychological distinction between mediate and imnicdU 
ate beliefs is one which, so it seems to me, everj^one must acknowledge. 
Surely we ah have L^eliefs which we have come to hold because wc have 
inferred them from other beliefs of ours. But inference cannot be the 
sole mode of belief-formation. There must be some processes other 
than inference that produce beliefs in us; otherwise inference would 
have nothing to do its work on. Those will be processes that produce 
beliefs immediately. 

What disLinguishes the foundationalist from his fellow epistemolo- 
gists is that he articulates his account of the presence and absents 
of whatever mi^ht be the doxastic merit on which he has his eye in the 



S2 FtsUGSf?piiy ofR^ti^kvf w the 21st Century 



following way: first he offers an account of whal brings it about that 
tl:tc merit attaches to those lmmcd]alclv held beliefs to vvliieh it does 
attach, and under ^^hat circumstances this is brought about. Attd then 
he offers an accouiil of the circumstances under whicli inference 
succeeds in transferring that merit from immediately held l>cliefs 
which already possess it, to behefs inferred from those- <0f course, 
some beliefs may be produced jointly by immediate-belief- formation 
processes and mediate-helief-formation processes.) 

This description simply does not fit tiie basic structure? of Plantinga^s 
account of warrant, ol^ Alston's account of those beliefs which arc justi- 
fied by their being evoked by leligious experience, nor of my account 
of entitlement- Let me elaborate this claim just a bit for Plantinga^s 
account of warrant. 

A rou^h description of PIantin;^a's account ls this: a behef is war- 
ranted just in case it is produced by faculties aimed at truth which 
a;e functioning property, in situations for which those faculties were 
designed to work thus. Notice that nowhere here is the distinction 
between immediate and mediate beliefs appealed to. Plantinga^s account 
of what brings it about that warrant accrues to a behef does not, In its 
basic structure, exhibii the bipartite structure definitive of foundational- 
ist accounts. Whether or not the belief under consideration is mediate or 
linmcdiale, the relevant question is always and only whether It was pro- 
duced by a faculty aimed at truth functioning properly in a situation for 
which it was designed. The unified structure which Plantinga's theory 
exhibits allies It, in this regard^ with coherentist accounts - though of 
course it^s also not a coherentist theory. 

It is true that something mote requires to be said. Ptantinga does 
accept the distinction between mediate and immediate modes of belief- 
formation, hideed, when he applies his general account of warrant to 
an analysis of the proper functioniitg of our actual faculties of bclief- 
formation/he finds it essential to make the distinction- At this second 
level, then, hts account does exhibit a foundationalist character; noth- 
\ng of the sort happens in a pure coherentist theory. Furthermore, the 
outcome of his anal)^'sis at this second level is that the scope of imme- 
diately formed beliefs wliich are warranted Is considerably wider than 
ihc classical foundationalist would acknowledge. Nonetheless il remains 
true that hi its basic stmcttue, Plantiiiga's theory is not an expanded 
foundational Lsm but is not a foundationalism at alL 

Let me call attention to another aspect of the significance of 
Reformed Epistcniology by casting a somewhat different light on the 
basic structure of the positive epistcraological theories which Itave 



Nkhofds Woitprstojff^ 5:^ 



been developed, in this third stage of their movement, by the 

Reformed epislcinologists- {\ have in mind here epistcinology proper^ 
not Wisseiischnfisiehre.) Ever since Flato, a certain picture of the ideally 
formed belief h^is haunted Western philosophy^ and in particular^ the 
philosophy of religion. Sometimes the picture has been incorporated 
within a theory of knowledge, at other times, williin a theory of sci- 
encc, on yet other occasions^ within a theory of entitlement - and dvcj 
and over, within a theory of certitude. 

Here is the picture. Fundamental in the life of the mind is acqiiainhm-ce 
wUh entities, and awareness of haviitg acquainLaiice with entities. What I 
call 'acquaintance"" is what Kant called Ansdnmmis - standardly, though 
not very happily, translated in the English versions of Kant as ^inltiitioiV. 
Or to look at the same thing from the other side: fundamental in the life 
of the mind is presaice - cnLitLcs presenting themselves to us, puttii:kg 
in their appearance to us. Consider the definite description: 'the dizzi- 
ness you felt when you rode that merry-go-round yesterday". If you did 
in fact feel dizzy upon riding a merry-go-round yesterday, then 1 can 
use that definite description to pick out that particular dizziness - to 
pick it out w^ell enough to make assertions about It, for example. 
Nonetheless, that particular dizziness was never part of the intuitional 
content of my mind; / was never acquainted with it^ it was never 
presented to me. My contact with it is - and was - very different from 
my contact with the dizziness / felt when / rode that merry-go-round 
yesterday Thiit dizziness was present to me; I was acquainted with it. 

To say it again: acquaintance, and its converse, presence^ are in their 
various modes fundamental to the life of the mind. Perception has 
intuitional content^ memory has intuitional content, introspeelton has 
intuitional content, intellection {reason) Lias intuitional content. Surely 
there could be no human inind devoid of all these; perhaps there could 
Ik no such mind at all. (To assure oneself that tlie four activities just 
mentioned do all have an intuitional component, contrast picking out 
some entity by means of a definite description, with perceivings 
remembering, introspecting, or Intellecting that entity, or an entity of 
tliat sort.) VVhatevcrn if anylliing, may be true in the currently fashion- 
able diatribes against presence, it cannot be that the mind is devoid of 
intuitional content. 

Among the entities with which wc have acquaintance are facts: I per- 
ceive that the sufs is rising , 1 introspect that I am ftt/ijj^ rather dizzy ^ i 
remember that the ride mmi^ me feel dizzy, I intellect that the propositioiiy 
green is a cclottr, is necessarily true- And now for llie picture of the 
ideally formed iKlief: sometimes^ so it has been claimed and assumed^ 



54 fhiiGSGptiy ofR^ti^w}! w the 21st Century 



oiic^s acquaintance with some fact^ coupled^ if necessary^ with one's 
awareness of that acquainLancen produces in one a belief whose propo- 
sitiona! content corresponds to the fact ivith Avhich one is acquainted^ 
My acquaintance with the fact that 1 am fcclan^ rather dizzy produces 
in me the belief that i am feeling rather dizzj^ The content of my belief 
is^ as it were, read directly off liie fact with which [ have acquaintance. 
How could such a belief possibly be mistaken^ Lt^s been asked. It must 
be Lhe case that it is certain. 

That's one type of Ideally formed belief, the first grade, as it were: the 
belief formed l^jy one's acquaintance with a fact to which the pioposi- 
tional content of the belief corresponds. There is a second type^ of a 
■somewhat lower grade: the Iwlief formed by one's acquaintance witii 
the faa that the prepositional content of the belief is logically entailed 
by propositions corresponding to facts of which one is aware. In such a 
case^ the certainty of one's belief concerning the premises, coupled with 
the certainty of one's belief concerning the entailment, is transmitted 
to one's belief of the conclusion; it too is certain for one. What 
accounts for the fact that such a belief will typically be of a lower grade 
than the highest is that one may tiavc acquaintance with the facts 
corresponding Lo the premises in an argument, and acquaintance with 
the fact that those premises deductively support the conclusion^ 
without having acquaintance with the fact corresponding to the con-^ 
elusion- Indeed, therein lies the point of such arguments- Deductive 
arguments^ if grounded in acquaintance, carry us beyond aci^ualntance 
while yet preserving certitude. 

iSomc writers - such as John Locke - have held tliat there is a third 
grade of ideally formed beliefs^ viz,, the belief formed by one's acquain- 
tance with the fact thaL the propositional content of the belief ispiobiible 
relative to facts with which one has acquaintance- It was especially 
inductive arguments that Locke had in mind. Locke recognized that 
Inductive arguments are incapable of transmitting certainty to the con^ 
elusion; hence beliefs thus formed are of a lois^cr grade than the others. 
Nonetheless, Locke quite clearly regarded mductlve arguments as like 
deductive In that, if one has collected a satisfactory body of evidence as 
premises, and if one is acquainted with the facts corresponding to the 
premises and witli Liie fact that the conclusion is more probable than 
not on those premises, tlien one's acceptance of the conclusion is 
entirely grounded in acquaintance. 

One can see wliy The Doxastie Ideal has had the appeal which it has 
had: there is something admirable about beliefs which measure up to 
the Ideal - especially^ about beliefs which measure up to the first stage 



Nicholas W:}iter.^torJf' 5S 

of the Ideal. A belief evoked by acquaintance with the fact to which 
the propositional content of [he belief corresponds: what could be 
bctterp more satisfying, than that, and more reassuring] A Ix^licf evoked 
by acquaintance with the fact that the propositional content of the 
belief Is entailed by beliefs of the first sort: such a Ix^iief is on\y slightly 
less satisfying- But the point to be made here is that such beliefs are 
not ideal fur us Immafs bangs, in our situatio}!. What has been taken to 
be The Doxa'itk kieaS is not ideal for ns. The failure of a belief to mea- 
5ure up to the Ideal does not, so far forth, point to a deficiency which 
we hurrsiifs beings ought to remove^ or eveit to a deficiency which it 
would be iksirabk for us to remove. Our belief-forming constitution 
docs not nieasute up to the supposed ideal in its indigenous workings; 
nor is it possible to revise its workings so that those workings do all 
measure up to the supposed ideal. And even if it were possible, even if 
we could somehow mana^ to reshape our belief-forming self so that it 
conformed in its workings to the supposed ideal, we would find our- 
selves with too scanty a body of beliefs for life to continue. Once again^ 
wlien w-e look deep into human existence, we spy tmst. 

It was the two great eighteenth-century Scotsmen^ David Hume and 
Thomas Reid, who firstn poweaiully and directly, challenged The Doxasiic 
Ideal by arguing that, whatever philosophers might prefer, our human 
condiilon Is such that vast numl:kers of the beliefs we have, and with- 
out which we could not live, were neither formed in accord with The 
Doxastie Ideal nor could be so formed, while yet being entitled, 
warranted, justified, or wliat have you. 

Hume argued the case most pow^crfully for lieliefs about the fiitul^ 
formed by induction. 1 see that the car ahead of me has veered off the 
mountain road and is now unsupported in the air; that experience 
evokes in me Immediately the belief that the car will descend with 
increasing rapidity. The propositional contcitt of the belief does not 
correspond to the fact perceived. It may be, however, that whaL 
accounts for the formation of the belief that the car will descend with 
increasing rapidity is that I make a logically valid inference to this 
from another belief that I surely form, namely, that the car is now 
unsupported in the air - perhaps with some othe: beliefs tossed in 
which 1 have arrived at by the exercise of reason? Not at all, argued 
Hume. What accoimts for the formation of the belief that the car will 
descend with increasing rapidity is not an exercise of reason but Just 
the habit, or custom, which has been formed in me by my experience 
of many similar such events. Reid fully accepted this analysis hy Hume 
of the formation of inductive beliefs^ and went on to offer a broadly 



56 fhUosGpiiy ofRiiti^kvf w the 21st Century 



similar accounl of perceptual bcltcfSj of n^cmoiial beliefs^ iiid of l>clLcfs 
fonncd by testimony- All such beliefs are formed in us by virtue of out 
■"hard wiring^, not by the employment of rational inference, None h 
mtiomiUy groiuhie^i. 

One aspect of the significance of Reformed Eplslemolog\^, intimately 
relaLcd to its use of Rcid to explicate Calvin's religious anthropology, is 
that it repudiates The Doxastic Ideal gcncrallyj and repudiates it, in 
particular, for religious beliefs. Consider one of Plantinga's examples. 
One looks up at night and perceives a starry sky - one perceives that 
there's a vast starry sky before one. That perception in turn evokes in 
one immcdiatelv the belief that God must have made all this. This 
latter belief may very well be warranted, Plantinga argues. Yet the 
content of the belief - namely, that God must have made alt this - docs 
not correspond to the fact one perceives - namely, that there's a starry 
sky before one. It goes beyond that. In declaring chat the belief evoked 
may well have warranty Plantinga is so far forth repudiating The 
Doxasttc IdeaL 

Or consider one of tlie cases I cite in my discussion of entitled rcli-^ 
gious tKlief in Divine Discourse. Augiistinc hears a child over the ;3^ardcn 
ivall chanting lake and read, take and read'. After some quick reflecllon, 
Augustine finds this uncanny. Perhaps he beliews that it is uncanny; 
more likely he hears it as uucmniy. It quickly occurs to hlni that maybe 
(he chant is part of a game; but he can^t think of any such game. That^s 
really a throw away pointy however; it makes no difference one way or 
the other. Augustine has an intimation that the words, "whatever led 
the child to chant themj may well be appropriate to his condition; 
that's what makes the chanting acquire an uncanny character for him. 
And that experience evokes in him immediately the belief that God 
is speaking to him, telling him to open his copy of Paul's Epistles 
and read. 

If this is liow it went - Augustine's description is too brief for us to be 
sure of all the details - the resultant beliefj in its mode of formation, 
certainly does not measure up to The Doxasrlc Ideal. The proposicional 
content of the belief which gets formed in Augustine is that God is 
speaking to him. But the fact which he hears is the fact of a child chant- 
ing 'toiie lege/ or rather, the fact of the uncannincss of the child's chant- 
ing 'toUe lege' within his earshot right ilien. Nonetheless Augustine was, 
so I argue, entitled to the belief tlial God %vas speaking to him. 

In conclusion, let me return to a point which ! raised earlier but then 
reserved for later discussion. The Reformed Episteniologist regards a 
great deal of religious language as being nlxmt God; that is to say^ he is 



Nicholas W:}iter.^torJf' S7 

of ihc view that in our use of rcli^ous language^ wc often refer to God- 
He is furthermore oE the view thai often, having referred to God^ we 
predicate something of that to which we referred- and he regards such 
predications as true or false of God^ depending on the facts of the mat- 
ter It I exclaim with the Psalmist, 'Bless the Lord, O my soul, and all 
that is within me, bless God^s holy name/ I am referring to God hut 
not predicating anything of God^ by no means all language about God 
is assertory in character. This is a point thaL the Wittgensteinlaas are 
fond of making; and the Reformed epistemologist heartil)^ agrees. Non- 
assertory 'God-talk' may nonetheless incorporate references to God^ as 
the example just given illustrates. And a good deal of language about 
God is in fact assertory; it docs predicate something of that to which 
one referred, v\z., God. 

My interpretation of the mainline Wittgensteiiiians is that ihey deny 
that we ever refer to God^ and also dcny^ conscqLLcntlyj that we ever 
predicate things of God. ""God-talk"" Is not to be construed as Incorporat- 
ing references to God and as predicating something of that to which 
one referred. To conclude my discussion I propose to join the fray on 
this issue - without any expectatLoi:i that my intervention will prove 
decisive! 

Let me approach the battleground by expressing my disagreement 
wiLh Phillips on what he sees as the status of the issue within Reformed 
Epistemology. At several points, Phillips describes the Reformed episte- 
mologisl as trying to 'justify^ our 'epistemic practices' - by which lie 
meai:fcSH trying to show that our modes of belief- formation are reliable^ in 
that the beliefs they produce correspond to objective realityJ^ I submit 
that the Reformed epistemologist attempts no sucli thing. To the con- 
trary, Reformed cpislemologists regularly cite Reid's argument against 
the sceptic to the effect that^ in the nature of the case^ such an attempt 
wUl prove either arbitrary or self -^delca ting. 

^EpLstemic practices' is an ambiguous term. It might mean, as I just 
now, following IHiillips, took it to mean^ moiic!^ of belief fomiatlon. But it 
might also mean, modes of belief evafuatiofi. It is practices of belief evalua- 
tion that the Reformed epistemologist has in tl:;e centre of his attention. 
We humafi beings engage in the practice of evaluating our beliefs as 
warranted, as rational, as justified, as cases of knowledge, as entitled, 
and so forth. The Reformed epistemologist doesn't invent these prac- 
tices. He finds themn and fiiids Ehat he himself is apartlcipaiiL in diem. 
And he accepts Ihcm. It's not his goat to criticize them in any general 
sort of way; witness i^lantinga's 'epiitemology from below\ Though he, 
like everybody elsc^ thinks that people make mistakes in what they 



5S fhUo.wpiiy ofRiiti^kvf w the 21st Century 



appraise as warrantcdn as entitled^ and so fojcLh^ he is not of the view 
that everybody is almost entirely ivroiig about knowledge, almost 
entirely wrong about entitlement and so fortli. In the first and second 
:Stages of Lhc movenicnl, what the Reformed cpistemolo^ist subjected 
to critique w^as not our practices of dosastic evaluation but the anaij^^is 
and critique of those practices offered by the classical foundationatists. 
in the third stage of the movemcntj his goal has been lo give his own 
positive account of these practices of evaluation. On this point, then, 
there^s no dispute betiveen the Reformed cpistemologist and the 
Wiltgcnsteinian philosopher of religion. 

Rather often VVitt^ensteinian philosophers of religion have been 
charged vsllh offering an atheistic account of religious language. 
'Absolutely not/ they say, bridling at the charge. Ifs their view that the 
existence of God is taken for granted in all that the theistically religious 
person believes and says. The last thing such a person will say Is^ God 
does not exist/ The 'grammar^ of Ihelstic religious language requires not 
5a)Tng that- Saying that would be tantamount to repudiating one's 
(theislic} rcligLcn- Of course theistically religious people^ when engaged 
In their religious way of life, don't go around saying, 'God exists/ 
Instead they praise God, hless God, pctiLion God, and so forlh_ But if 
pressed on the issue^ they will say emphatically^ 'God exists' - though 
it falls strangely on their ears- In shorln this way of getting at the fun- 
damental issue w^hich divides Reformed epistcmologists from mainline 
Wiltgenstcinian philosophers of religion proves a dead-end- 
Other such dead-ends could be explored. But let me, on this occa- 
sicn^ resist entering all such dead-ends and state without further ado 
what r regard as tlic fundamental point of dispute. Tliat i^ this: is it 
possible to refer to God; and, having referred^ is it possible to prt'dk ate 
things of God? 

Let^s take D.Z- Ptiillips as the paradigmatic Witlgcnsteinian philoso- 
pher of religion. In some of the passages in which Phillips discusses God 
and reference^ what he says, taken strictly^ is not that we cannot refer to 
God, but that God is not an object to w^hich we can refer, with the con- 
text suggesting that by an ^ob]cct\ i'hillips means an entity occupying 
a place in space. In one passage he says^ for exanipten Talk of God^s 
existence or reality cannot be considered as talk about the existence of 
an object- Neither can questions about whether we mean the same by 
'^Gpd'"' be construed as whether we are referring to the same object. ""^-^ 
Now I myself find it extremely unlikely that anybody likely to read 
Phillips's w^ritings docs believe that God is an object occupying space; 
accordingly^ given the rules of 'conversational implicatioii^ one asks 



Nicholas W:}iter.^torJf' 59 

oneself whether perhaps Phillips docsn^t mean to say oi suggest some- 
thing niorCn or something else. Why bother lelling us that God Is not a 
spaflal object? 

This query gains added force from the rhetorical structure of some of 
the relevant passa^s. Here Is an example of what 1 have in mind: 

Ifn ... having heard of people praising the Creator of heaven and eajfthn 
glorifying the Father of us all, feeling answerable to the t>nc ivho sees 
all, someone were to say, 'But these arc only religious perspectives^ 
show inc what they refer to'^ this would be a misunderstandiiig of 
the ^ammar of such perspective.-.. The religious pictures give one a 
language in ^vhich it is possible Co think about human hfe in a ceT- 
taln way. The pictures ...provide ihe logical space within which 
such thoughts eaii have a place. Whcii these thoughts arc found in 
worship^ the praising and the glorifying does not refer to some 
object called God. Ralhcrn the expression of such praise and ^lory is 
what we call the worship of God.^^ 

The imagined interlocutor asJa to be shown what the religious perspec- 
tives refer to. Now if by 'show' he^s askhig to have the spatial object 
called God displayed to him, then indeed he's deeply confused -though 
to iiitcrpiet his words thus is to interpret them with a woodcnness that 
Phillips would rightly leap upon if exhibited in some philosopher's 
Intcrprctalion of religious language. But let Ihat pass. Phillips does not 
respond to this Imaj^incd remark by correcting the confusion about 
tlic nature of God which the remark (on the Interpretation being con- 
S^ercd) exhibits. Instead he ma'kes quite a different point. What he 
says is that 'The religious pictures give one a language in which it is 
possible to think about human life in a certain way^ - not^ notice^ a 
language in which it is possible to think ^bout Ooii ami Ood^s reiatkm to 
human life in a certain way, but a language in which it Is possible to 
think about imnkiff iifc in a certain way. So too^ after remarking, two 
sentences later, that "^the praising and the glorifying does not refer 
to some object called God/ he goes on to say that 'the expression of 
such praise and glory is what we call the worship of God\ Tf the 
mistake of the interlocutor was to suppose that God is a spatial object 
which can be refcrted to, how w^ould this be an answer to that? In short, 
tlie rhetorical structure of tlic passage suggests that the worship of God 
has nothing at all to do with w^hethcr there's any reference to God^ and 
w^hethcr praise is addressed to tlic being referred to. Worship of God 
only has to do with whether certain 'thoughts are found in worship'. 



60 FtsUGSf?piiy ofR^ti^w}! w f/re 21st Century 

Finally, thcHj consider this passage: 

In face of what is given, the believer kneels. Talk of ^God' has Its 5ense 
ill this reaction. It is not the name of an individual; ll docs not refer 
to anything-.-- U is all too easy to conclude Ihat ii icligious expres- 
sions which involve talk of God are nol referring expres-sions, if no 
object corresponds to such talk, such expressions caiinot say any- 
thing nor can they be held lo be Imc. In this chapter, however^ we 
have seen that this argumenL contains unwarrantable assumptions. 
We have argued for olhcr possibilities. When these arc recognized we 
see that religious expressions of praise, glory, etc. are not referring 
expressions. These activities are expressive in character, and what 
they express is called the AYorship of God. Is it reductionism to say 
tiiaL wiiat is meant by the reality of God is to be foiind in certain 
pictures which say themselves? ^^ 



Now all ambiguity has been dissipated. The word 'God' do^^ not refer 
to anytfu}!^. Initially vs^e had some reason to think that the mistake 
of the interlocutor was to suppose that in our use of ^God talk' we refei 
to a ^piitinl oh)ect_ Noiv we see that, on Phillips'5 view, his mistake 
goes deeper; he doesn't get home free by conceding that^ when using 
'God talk'n we refer to a being who transcends this spatial order. 
The mistake of the interlocutor wa^ in assuming that 'God talk^ is refer- 
ential. Such speech is purely expressive in character; praise is expres- 
sive activity- And when the one who praises uses ^God talk\ such 
expressive activity fint is what constitutes ihe worsliip of God. Thcrc^s 
nothing more to the worship of God than that. Now we understand 
why the passages quoted earlier liave the rhetorlcai structure to whicli 
I pointed- 

flilllips is remarkahty chary of telling us why on his view, 'God taJk' 
is purely expressive - why the w^oid ^God\ as used by religious people, 
'does not refer to anj^hing^ Sometimes one gets the impression that 
Jfs a doctrine of reference whicli Is at work: we can only refer to that 
which occupies a place in space. At other times one gets the Impression 
that what's operating is a certain theolog}^, along the lines of Plotinus, 
Kant and Tlllich: God is not a one-among-others that can be picked 
out_ Best not to speculate, however. Phillips never lays out his reasons; 
he contents himself with lieaping ridicule on anyone wlio uses the 
word Mndividuar or 'object' when speaking of God, never telling us 
what word he himself prefers, If any, and on insisting that religious dis- 
course is in good measure not assertory in character. 



Nichofds WGiter.^tojff^ 61 



Now it's possible thai Phillips didn^l really mean what he said in the 
passages to which I have poinlcd from RcU^ion witiiout Exphmatioii. But 
just a5 I am not aware of any pas-sage in which Phillips explains why he 
holds that the word Xxod^ 'does not refer to anything'', so loo 1 am not 
aware of any in which, to correct misinterpretations of his thought, he 
says flat out that of course he hclieves that 'God^ is used by theists to 
refer; all he ever wanted to say was that God is not a spatii}! object - or 
all he ever wauled to say was that Plolluus was right in holding that 
God is not a one-among-othcrs. So I think w^e have no option but to 
hold that Phillips did and docs mean what he said there. 

It's on this issue of reference and predication concerning God (along 
with the issue of wliether theistic language implies existential quantifica- 
tions over God) that Phillips's version of Wilt^enstelniantsm clashes most 
directly with Reformed Epistemolo^^ For Ihc Reformed epistemologlst 
understands himself^ when using 'God talk', as referring to God. And 
though one can refer to God Vnlthoul predicating somelliing of God - as 
when the psaEmist enjoins himself to bless God's holy name - the 
Reformed epistemologist understands himself as often going on to 
predicate things of Gckj^ these predications then being true or false of 
God depending on the fact of the matter The Reformed epistemologlst 
understands his religious cohorts as regularly doing the same things he 
does - namclyj refer to God and predicate things of God. Thus the 
Reformed epistemologist holds that a great deal of theistic religious 
language is used refercntLally and predicalively concerning God^ and 
that a great deal of it entails propositions expressed with sentences 
which quantify over God- If there is no such being as Godj, thcn^ on 
the account of theistic religious language wliich is taken for granted by 
the Reformed epistemologlst, theistic religious language misfires in a 
most radical way. For of course one cannot refer to^ and predicate 
things of, what there isn't. 

Who's right on this issue? No doubt there's room here for a good 
deal of philosophical lo4ng and fro-ing^ each side pressing the other 
for reasons for his position^ questioning those reasons, tr\1ng to extract 
'absurd' consequences from the other's position, and so on. It's my 
own guess, however, that when the dust has settled, it's going to come 
down to what those who use Ihetstic language in a serious religious 
way, and who grasp the philosophical issues at stake, understand them- 
selves as intending to do when they use ^God calk'. 

1 judge myself to he such a person, and my fellow Reformed episte- 
mologists to be such as well. And we understand ourselves, when using 
'God talk', to be intending lo refer to God and (often) lo predicate 



&2 FtsUosoptiy ofRiiti^w}! w the 21st Century 



things of God; likewise wc undcfstand ourselves^ when using thcistic 

language, to be saying things which imply that there Is a being such 
that !t is identical with God. If wc were pcRuadf^d that those intentions 
were fundamentally misguided because there is no such bein;^ as God, 
then we would cease using 'Gcd talk' - other than to Join our atheist 
friends in exclaiming, Thank God it's Ftiday!^ WhaE^s the poinl of 
talking about God saving us if theie^s no God to do the savingJ 

D-Z- Phillips Ls also someone who uses theistic language in a serious 
religious way, and who understands the philosophical issues at stake. 
Yet he docs not understand himself to be meaning to use 'God talk' rcf- 
eientially and predlcatively. 

'So w^haf s the solution? One possibility is that one or the other of us 
fails to understand our own intentions in using 'God talk""- What 
strikes me as much more plausible is that wc simply use theistic 
language in hindamentally different ways. Phillips offers what we can 
assume to Ik an accurate deseriplion of how he and his fellow main- 
line Wittgensteinians use theistic language; I gave what I take to be an 
accurate description of how 1 and my fellow Reformed cpistemologists 
use thcistic language. 5o we're both right - provided that wc Iwth 
avoid univer^alization_ Philltps^s account holds for himself and main- 
line Wittgensteinians^ but not for me and my fellow^ Reformed cpiste- 
mologists; my account holds for myself and my fellow Reformed 
epistcmologists, but not for mainline Wittgensteinians. 

What holds for all the others - for all the other users of theistic 
language? My own guess is that almost all of themp if they saw^ the 
issue^ would say that chey meant to be using theistic language as 1 and 
my fellow Reformed episteuiologists use it not as Phillips uses it. 
Almost all of them would feel profoundly disillusioned if they came to 
the view that God is not among that which is available for reference 
and predication - for the reason that it's not true that there exists a 
being which is God. If Phillips's religious use of theistic language con- 
forms to his description, then his use represents a revision of how such 
language has traditionally been used; his religious use of such language 
is a revisionist use. 

Phillips understands himself, in his 'writings^ as^ speaking not reli- 
giously but philosophically; and ovef and over he sa)^ that his aim, as 
philosopher, is not to revise but describe. His description does not 
hold, howcvern for how Itcformed epislemologists use theistic lan- 
guage; nor, I contend, for how most people use such language. His 
description holds only for a ralh^r select group of Wittgensteinians and 
their allies. Yet his words regularly carry the suggestion that he is 



describing al! serious ictigious use of thcistic language. Accordingly^ his 
description Is, for most people, a .fm^descripEion. And should his dis- 
cussion succeed in getting sonio people to think they arc using thcistic 
language in his way^ when in fact they have been using it in any way, 
then his discussion threatens to do what he says he wants at all cost to 
avoid doing; namely^ it threatens to function not as description but as 
revision. 



Notes 



1 _ LTniveriitj^ of Notre Dame Press. 

2. Nous, March 19S1. 

3. Grand Rapids^ Eerdfnan:; Pubhshing C(i_ 

4. Ithdcaj Cornell Univer_sitv Press. 

5. Grand Rapids: Eerdmanji PuhJLsiiing Co_ 

6. New York" Rcnitiedge, 19SB. 
7 ibid-, p- 259- 

B. iVf, for example^ ibid., pp- 32-3_ 

9. Oxford! Oxford University Prew, 1993. 1993 and IfKlO. 

10- Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995. 

LI- Oxford: O-xford University Press, 1997. 

12- 5ffj for e-xample^ ibid., p- 3S- 

13- RL'ii,^ia}i withoitl Expiiuiation ^Oxford: Biack^veil^ i^^^Jj P- 1^4. 
14. ibid-, pp, 148-9- 

Li. Ibid-, pp. 148, ISO- 



5 

On Behalf of the Evidentialist 
a Response to Wolterstorff 

Stephen /. tV)^A:jfm 



Why don't you just scrap this God iTU^ncss, says one of my 
bitter suffering friends, it's a rotten woild^ you and I have been 
shafted^ and that's that. 

I'm pinned down. When I survey this gigantic intricate 
world, I cannot believe that it just came abouL I do not mean 
that I have some good arguments for its being made and that I 
beHeve in the ar^ments. 3^ mcati that ihis conviction wells up 
irresistibly within me wlien 1 contemplate the world. 

Nicholas Woltcistorff^ Lumeutfof a Son 

Reformed epistemology as rtHgioiis philosophy 

Nicholas WoltersLorff has j^iven us an illuminating account of the 
development and main claims of Reformed Epistcmology- Reformed 
Epistemology, he has stressed^ seeks to provide an account of the 
epistcmological status of thetstic belief, not an overall philosophy 
of religion. In tlic 1980s^ its project was priniartly negative aiming to 
overcome the evidentialist challenge, alleging that theistic belief is 
lacking in warrant or entitlement if it is not supported by good rea- 
sons. So this phase was brush-clearing, seeking to clear away evidential- 
ist bramble. In the 1990s, its projeit has become more positive, aiming, 
we might say, to grow^ in the place of the bramble, a garden of ncw^ 
cpistcmologleal insights about wliat gives theistlc belief Its various 
doxastlc merits, and what makes it deeply relevant to the theoretical 
and interpretive disciplines. 

Reformed t-pistemology iSj Wolterstorff has stressed, not a philosophy 
of religion; but his description of its roots indicate that it is a religious 
philosophy^ For it is rooted in the vision of nco-Calvlnism, especially as 



&4 



Stephen /. tV>-"jt.sfrii 65 

articulated by Abiahani Kuyper And that vision Is itself religious In 
characicr. What, cpistcmolo^Leally spcakiiig, is at its heart? It is, I 
think, that God Lias made each of us so that we can. through God's 
regenerating and sanctifying worlt in our livcs^ increasingly come to 
know God in a cognltivcly direct way- Direct does not here mean 
individualistic. Reformed thinkers prize tlic Scrlpltircs, the community 
wiiich is the priesthood of all bclieverSj the sacraments^ and the 
preaching of the Word. So the idea of directness is not that we need 
these things - the Word, the sacraments, the community less and less as 
wc spiritually mature; to the contrary, we need these things more and 
more. Rather^ the idea is that God has made us so that as ive mature, 
our knowing God through these things rests more and more on some- 
thing involving God's own testimony in our hearts, as he uses these 
things 10 hring us to Himself. 

This conception of religious knowing is stressed by Calvin and later 
reformed theologians (thougli of course it can also be found within 
other currents within the great river of Christian tradition as wcllh Tt 
is itself a religious vision^ part of a religious worldview. The Reformed 
Epistemologists (and here 1 mean Plantinga, Wolterstorff and William 
Alston, an Episcopalian who is a kind of honorary Reformed thinker) 
liave used de^^clopments In meta-cpistemology to give a philosophical 
elaboration and deployment of this vision^ and used the vision to 
propel new developments in epistemology. They thus tliemselves 
exemplify the thesis that Christian theism is deeply relevant to tlie 
theoretical and interpretative disciplines. 



Objections 



What, then, of objections to Reformed cpisteniology? In addition to 

objections discussed by Wolterstorff, these have come from three main 

quarters. 

Firsc, there are objections from the quarters of analytic philosophers 
who think thcistic religion is or may be unreasonable due to evidcn- 
tialist deficiencies. 

Second, there are objcetioiisfrom what we might call the pluralists 
those who find Reformed cpistemolog)^ too complacent in what it says 
or fails to say about rival sources of insight which contlict with the 
deliverances of theistic practice. One group of rivals consists of other 
religious traditions; another source consists of secular sources of 
insight, like Nietzsche^ Freud and Marx. 



&6 fhUti^^ptiy ofR^ti^w}! w the 21st Century 

Thirdj there are objections from thcists vslio think Reformed episte- 
molog\^ has insufflclenl appreciation for llie value of evidential support 
for various theistic beliefs. Catholic critics have faulted Reformed 
IhinkcTS for depreciating the role of natural theology. Evangelical critics 
have pleaded /or more recognition of the importance of Christian 
apDiogetics. not so much in the tradition of natural theology but in the 
tradition of evidences of Christianity^ reasoned defences of the reliabil- 
ity of the gospels, the historicity of the resurrection of Jesus, and so on. 

These three sources of objections overlap, of course, and certain com- 
mon themes emerge. In particular, many (though not all) of the critics 
think that there is more to be said on behalf of e\adcntlalism than 
Reformed thinkers have granted. And this is the issue 1 would like to 
press. 1 shall do so in my own way, since I know it l>est. Wolterstorff 
remarks that one characteristic of the positive phase of Reformed epis- 
temolog\^ has been an almost total absence of further ground clearing. 
There has becii little looking backward at the pile of evldentialist bram- 
ble that was cleared. I shall poke around In the bramblCn to see if there 
might still not be a green branch thai belongs In the Reformed garden. 

What is tht real issue? 



Lcfs begin by going back to the issue dividing Reformed thinkers from 
their polemical partner, the cvidcntialists. That issue is whether theistic 
belief needs evidence. EvidentialLsts think that it does^ Reformed episte- 
mologists think that it doesn't. They urge, instead, that theistic belief, at 
its epistcmic best^ Is a 'properly basic' belief^ akin to our beliefs in physi- 
1^1 objects or the past or other minds. I shall call this thesis basicalism, 
and shall often refer to a Reformed Epistemologlst as a basicalist. It is 
perhaps an ugly term, but it provides the right contrast to evldentialist. 

BasleaHsts, then, say that theistic belief does not need evidence; 
belief in God, as Plantinga puts it (1983p p- 17) can be 'entirely right, 
proper, and rational without any evidence or argument at all\ Now it is 
crucial to realize that when basicalists say this, they are using the term 
evideiice in a marrow sense. This is, as Plantitiga himself fully realizes, 
a somewhat artificial sense. I believe I have two hands: do I have 
evidence of mv senses. So the mitumi sense of the word evidence is 
a broad sense, a sense that includes not only inferential arguments, but 
also direct or immediate justificrs like sensory evidence^ memory dispo- 
sitions, and so on. Reformed thinkers, however, are not using the term 
in this broad sense. When they speak of evidence, they mean, almost 
alwavSj inferential c^ddence. (Inferential evidence consists of other 



Stephen} f. Wyt:.^trn 67 

propositions wc believe^ from which wq infer the trutli of the belief in 
question-) When basicalists want to speak of n on -Inferential jusUfierSn 
th^^y use the term grounds rather than evidence. My belief that T have 
tivo hands docs not rest on evidence^ but on grounds. 

So the Great Dividing Issue between basicalists and cvidentialtsts is 
this^ Docs ihci^tic behcf Ji^if^J iviiieiice iff the min'ow inferi'fitinl wnse of 
evidence? Wc mi^ht think wc arc now clear about what the dividing 
issue Is. But arc wc? I do not think so. The notion of needing iniercn- 
tial evidence is far more slippcrj-' than one might think. 

What is it for a t^clicf to need inferential evidence? Our initial grasp of 
the notion tends to come from familiar examples. That the sun is shining 
outside my window is something I can just tell by looking and seeing; 
that 1 plus 1 is 2 IS something immediately obvious to my reason. Tliesc 
claims do not need inferential evidence; they can properly b^ believed 
in a basic fthat is, non infeTcntiall way. But I also believe things whose 
truth Is not obvious In any such basic way - that the sun is about 
9^ million miles away, or that 17 times 139 equals 2363^ or that atoms 
arc made of protons^ electrons and neutrons. So such claims, if they arc 
to be properly belte^'cd, need to be secured by infcEcncc of an appropri- 
ale sort_ Call them property inferential proposition's. 

But what docs it really mea}f, to say that these latter claims need 
inferential evidence? Take the claim about the sun; wc all surely agree 
that fn soTTie sense, it docs heed inferential evidence- (Wc also pre- 
5uineH of course, that it Ihf-s what it needs. The v%^ord 'needs' here is used 
in that sense that docs not imply a lacL The paradigm is Humans need 
watcr^ iiot I need a drink.) But who needs to know this evidence? Surely 
I do hot personally need to loioiv it. Certain astrDhomcrs who work on 
tliese things need to know it. And similarly for my belief that atoms 
arc made of electrons^ protons^ and ncutronsr for my belief to be okay^ 
it is not necessary for me lo know the evidence for this. Rather^ It is 
certain physicists that must know^ this evidence fand, of course, T must 
be in some sort of appropriate relation to them). 

''I must'? - for the sake of what? Imagine we learn, ten years from 
now, that scientists didn't really have this evidence for elections, but had 
instead been duped by some extremely clever conmen in Copc!iha^en. 
Does that mean you and 1, in 1999^ were improper in believing w-hat 
we did about electrons? That doesn't seem right_ Perhaps we Qookin^ 
back) would say our beliefs had some sort of defect^ but the defect docs 
not seem to be that we were improper in holding them. 

So the notion of needing inferential evidence is slippery in. two ways- 
Firsl, it is not easy to say what refution ttf the evidence is needed. And 



6B fhUo.wpiiy ofRiiti^w}! w the 21st Century 

second, it is nol easy to s^y what^ for the sake of winch evidence is 
needed- This Is so, I am suggesting, even when one thinks about simple 
scientific beliefs. EvidentLalism seems like the right stance to take 
toward these beliefs: it docs seem they arc things lliat need evidence- 
But it is not easy to spell out this means. 

Daxastic mt-rits 

Let mc now connect this to a point made by Woltcrstorff. He notes 

ihaL there arc a niulliplicity of doxaslic merits lliat beiiefs can have, (hi 
many twentieth-century disputes about the correct cxpltcation of what 
it is for a belief to be justified, he suggests thai rival theorists actually 
have different doxastic merits in niind, and thus have different expli- 
canda/) In partLcular, WoltcTstorff distinguishes between the merits of 
entitlement and warrant. He then proposes that Reformed epislemol-^ 
ogy (in Its negative phase) should be understood 

to be the claim^ for some particular doxastic merits that there are 
beliefs about God held immediately [non-infercntially] which possess 
that merit. 

Accordingly, he says^ in speaking of the negative pliase of Reformed 
Epistemology: 

we ou^ht not speak of Reformed Epistemolo^^ tout court, but of 
Refotmcd Episteniology concerning warranty of Reformed EpisLe- 
inology concerning cntitlcmcht, etc. 



Tliis is surely right systematical ly. But hisLoricallyn it seems to me that 
iliis particular distinction emerged only in the third positive phase of 
Reformed episteniologj^ With the exception of a single footnote, I find 
no cognizance of this distinction in FnitJi ami Riitioiujiity, Lhc ioctis 
ci{i^siciis of Reformed eplstemolog^^ in its negative, or evidentialism- 
ovcrcoming, piiasc. Xo^ in that phase iteforined thinkers aiways had in 
mind the doxastic merit of sathisulity. In asserting that theistic belief 
does not need evidence, they w^ere always claiming that theistic belief 
does not need evidence to be mtio}Uit. The distinctions they drew were 
distinctions helping to clarify the term rational, not to distinguish 
it from warrant. This means they tj/^vw.^ construed evidentialism as 
claiming that if the believer believes without basing his or her belief on 
evidence, then he or she is in some sense iiratiorhiL 



Stephen} f. Wyt:.strn 69 



Ration all ty-tvidtiitial ism 



Let us make this construal more expliclL Evidcntialtsm, so construed, 
says thelstic belief needs cvtdcTice if theists *irc to l>c rational for to 
avoid being irrational) in thcii: believing. Uut what is it^ to be ^rationar 
(or 'irrationar)? Reformed thinkers considered Lwo broad possibitiiies. 
The first is that being rational is a matter of fulfilling our intollcctual 
duties - our duties in matters of forming and regulating our beliefs. An 
irfailonal belief is one that violates these duties: irfationality, on Lhis 
construal, is doxastic sin. The second possibility construes rationality 
as a matter of manifesting certain 'excellences' in belie f-tormation. 
Richard has a brain tumour, causing him to form paranoid beliefs that 
liis wife is trying to kill him. Given the tumour^ he cannot help buL do 
this. We would not blame him, thinking he is violating some duty; 
nevertheless we might well call him irrational- ('How could Rich accuse 
me like that?/ his wife sobs. ""Jane', the doctor replies, Vou've got to 
remember the tumour is making him irrational/) Richard's believing 
falls short of standards, but these standards prescribe, not duties, but 
desirable or excellent ways of functioning, akin to standards informing 
our judgements about health. On this second construal^ Irrationality is 
not doxasric sin but doxastic sickness. 

Both explications capture important ordinary uses of the term 
'rational'. Moicovern they have an important commonality. On both, 
to deem a person irrational i^ to diagnose something as 'going wrong^ 
in the subject holding the belLef. It is something in thli believ- 
ing subject whether a culpable sin or a non-culpable sickness that 
needs changing or fixing, if things arc to be brought up to snufL 
Evaluations of rationality aitd irrationality are, wc can put it, .■jHif/i.'i.f- 
f€cti:^i:d evaluations. And cvldentialism, on this construal, is thus 
claiming that thcSstic belief needs Inferential evidence in order for the 
believing subject to be free of doxastlc sin or doxastic sicki:tcss in his 
believing. 

But in requiring that theistic belief be based on evideticep what 
reiatlon to evidence would such an evidentlallst then be claiming that 
theistic belief ""needs? If we are taking evidence to be needed for the 
sake of the rationality of the subject^ w^hat is needed is^ plausibly, that 
the believing subject herself be cognizant of the evidence and its evi- 
detitial bearing on the proposition she believes, and that she hold the 
behef partly because of this. Putative evidence will not contribute to an 
individual's being ratiomii In believing some proposition, unless this 
evidence fait within that individuates cognizance. So evidentialism, as 



70 FtsUosGpiiy ofR^ti^w}! w the 21st Century 

addressed by Reformed epistcmologistSH was alwa)^ construed as claiming 

iomclhing like iliis: 

Any incfivliiual believing IhaE God exists must^ in order to be nitio- 
n{il, hold this bchef on the basis of his/her ov/ii inference of tt from 
evidence. 

iLet us call Lhis riitloiiaJity-^vhientidllsm. 

Is avtrcoinlng rationalfty-evidentialism enough? 

But is rationality-evidenlialism really the right way to construe the 
evidcntiahst's core intulilon that theistic belief 'needs evidence'? Here 

consider Planttnga's counterexample agaitist one variety of ev'identialisi:Li 
construed in this way. Plantings considers a "14 year old who believes 
In God, having been raised in a community where everyone so believes. 
This young man, stipulates that Plantinga (1983^ p. '^'^): 

doesn't believe in God on the basis of evidence, lie has never heard 
of the cosmological, teleological, or oiitological arguments; in fact 
no one has ever presented him with any evidence at alL And 
although he has often been told about God, lie doesn't lake that 
testimony as evidence; he doesn't reason thus: everyone around 
here says that God loves us and cares for us; most of what everyone 
around here says is true; so probably tlnit^ true. Instead, he simply 
believes what hc^'s tauglit. 



Let's call this young man llanser- As Plantinga describes him. Hansel 
simply believes what his elders have taught htm about God. In so 
doingn is Mansel necessarily irrational? Rationality-evidcnlialism entails 
that he is; but surely, says Plantinga, it is quite implausible to think 
tliat in so believing, this youth is irrational in the sense of being in 
violation of his doxastic duties. Plantinga seems to me right about this; 
and he remains right, I believe, when v^e construe rationality In any of 
its plausible senses. The case of Hansel^ then, gives us reason to re|ect 
rationality-evidcntialism. 

But docs it tell against evldcntialism? Docs rejecting rationaJUy- 
evidenlialism mean rejecting the core intuition gf cvidentialism? To 
answer this, let us return to the point I made earlier: we are, almost all 
of us^ 'cvidentialists' about seme things. Almost all of us would want to 
say, intuitivclyj that a claim hke "electrons exist' needs Enfcrcnttal 



Stephen} f. Wyt:.^trn 71 

evidence. So most of us^ even it wc are Reformed thinkers about belief 
In Godp arc evldcntiallsl^ about electrons (or about the distance of the 
5un from the earth, and so on}. Now, in taktng it intuitively that elec- 
tron-belief 'needs evidence', arc we really endorsing ratiomiiity-tvuien' 
tmdsm about electrons? Are wc^ that is^ endorsing the claim: 

Any' individual believing that electrons exist must, in order to be 
rational^ hold his/hei belief that electrons exist on the basis of 
his/her own inference of It frotn evidence. 



Sufcly not. For suppose we consider some 14 -year-old jjd who believes 
that electrons exists having been raised in a community where every- 
one so believes. Gretcl, as we may call her doesn't believe in electrons 
on the basis of e^rEdcnce. She has ne\'er heard of the Millikan oil 
drop exj.x^rlmenl, of electron-diffraction, or of the quantum-theoretic 
explanations of spectroscopic data; in fact no one has ever presented 
her with any evidence for electrons at alL And although she has often 
been toM about electrons, she doesn't take that testimony as evidence; 
she doc5n t reason thus: everyone around here says that electrons exist; 
most of what everyone around here says is truc^ so probably that's true. 
Instead, she simply believes what she's taught. 

So Gretel, like I'lahscl, believes what her elders have taught her, 
without knowing the evidence. Now in our intuitive evidential ism 
about electrons, arc we saying that Grctcl is necessarily inational in 
this? One hopes not. Oniy an epistcinlc Scrooge would immedialely 
deem Grctcl as doxastically sick of sinful in believing her feachc^ as 
she does. Gretel (like Hansel) need not be irradonal In so believing; so 
fationatity-^'ideiitialism about electron belief is wrong. But docs this 
inean that our mtaitive LvideiitUiSisni about electrons is WTong? Does 
admitting that Grctel mi-^ht be okay entail admitting that we were 
wrong in our core intuition that electron theory 'needs Inferential 
evidence'? Surely not. What the case of Gretel teaches us is iwt that our 
Intuitive evldentialism about electrons is wrong; what it teaches us is 
that this evidenttalrsm is not faithfully captured or adequately expli- 
cated by rationality-evidentialism. 

But now let us suppose that what evidcntiahsts want to say about 
tlieistic belief is what wc^ almost all of us^ want to say (aiid have a hard 
time saying clearly) about electron-belief- Then rationality-evidentialism 
also does not faithfully capture what the evldentialist really wants to 
ScLV about thclstic belief. 



72 FtsUGSf?piiy ofRiiti^kvi w the 21st Cetitury 



Towards a more sensible evidentialism 



What, thciin do we mean, when we intuiUvely take electron-belief to 
'need eviideni:e7 There are two sub-quc5tlons to prc5? here. Firsts what 
sort of !'t'hit:ia}i to evidence do we take electron-belief {qnii hciicving) to 
need? The case of Gretel gives a clue here. She believes in electrons on 
the say-so or testimony or authority of her teacher in accord with what 
Rcid calls the Credulity Principle- And her teacher may have also 
acquired his belief in a similar way, so there is here a chain of testi- 
monial grounding. But such a chain must somewhere have an anchor: 
Neils may believe in electrons by trusting the say-so of Ernst; and Ernst^ 
by trusting the say-:^o of Wolfgang, but somewhere this chain must be 
anchored in someone's believing in electrons on a non-:estimonial 
basis. And when we, as e^ldentialistSn insist Ihat belief in electrons 
needs evidence, it is this ultimate anchoring iliat we have in mind. 

At the heart of our cvidentialism tegarding electrons^ in other words, is 
the intuition that inferential evidence for electrons needs to be available 
to the comimmitv of clectron~[>clieveTS. We do not mean that each Individ^ 
ucii electron-believer needs to have sorted through this evidence or even 
that each t>cliever is able to do so. (Hansel and Gretel may bQ so deficient 
in mathematical abilitv that the e^^'ldential case for electrons will forCT^er 
be beyond their grasp-} So, what is needed is that they be appropriately 
connected to an e I cetron-bel levins community, that there be an infer- 
ential case for electrons available to this community, and that some 
appioprtate sc^^nicnt of that community have processed this evidence. 
Tlie needed relation to evidence is a connmuutnihvi relation, rathe! 
than an individualistic one. 

The second question is this: for tlie sake of what doxastte merit Is 
evidence iieeded? Reformed epistemologists construe cvidentialism as 
claiming that it is needed for the sake of avoiding irrationality. But is 
tliis why a communitarian relation to evidence is needed? Consider 
again Gretel, believing in electrons on the say-so of her fifth grade 
teacher. We prcsumCp normally^ that an evidential case for electrons is 
indeed available to the community to which she and her teacher 
belong. But is It tlie rutioaaiit}^ of GreteFs belief that is enhanced by this 
presumed case? Well, imagine that we learn, ten years from now^ that 
our presumption was mistaken - that tliere is no good evidential case 
for electrons, and that the entire presumed case for electrons was an 
elaborate hoax perpetrated by clever connicn in Copenhagen in the 
1920s- Would learning this lead us to re\1se our judgement that Gretel 
was rational - would we^ that is, deem that she was (and all along had 



Stephen} f. Wyt:.^tr£i 7'^ 

been) imitionai in bctievinR Ln electrons on the say so of her teacher? 
.Surely not. Dut this means it \s not Toi tlie sake of (he rationality of her 
eloctron-^helief that we think sucti evidence i% needed. 

Warrant 

Wolterstorff refers to the distinction between entitlemcnl and warrant; 

let us now ask i^'hcther we c^in exphcate our e\1dentlahs!n about elec- 
trons in terms of warrant. The term is Plantinga's; he introduces it as a 
covering term to refer to that special whatcvcr-it-is which^ when added 
to a true belief, makes that true belief a case of knowledj^e. Classical 
Internalists took that Special Something to be a certain high degree of 
being justified in believing, where being iustified is closely allied to 
being lathtuif in one's believing. Rut externalists hold that it consLsLs 
in the knowing subject and known object being in a certain type of 
relallonship - a relationship 1 shall call 'successful epistemie hookup'. 
On 'reliabilisf theorieSn a belief has H\^rrant when it is produced by a 
'reliable process', a process that produces, or would produce^ true 
beliefs a sufficiently high proportion of the time. What matters^ say 
reliabili^ts^ i^ the 'externar fact that the pri>cess is reliable- not that the 
subject lias any awareness of or access to this reliability. Reliabihsts are 
externalists Ix^cause they reject the assumption, characteristic of classi- 
cal for pTC-Getticr'> internalism, that the additive that turns true belief 
into knowledge must be accessible within the subject^s perspective. 

To make the difference vivid (and determine whether your own 
prochvities are internalist of cKternalistj consider the following scenario. 
Cheech and Chong both wake up to the apparent sound of their alarm 
clock buzzing, and both form the belief that their alarm is buzzing. 
Now Cheech is woken by his real alarm clock actually buzzing- Chong, 
In contrastn has been abducted during the night by technologically 
advanced Alpha Centaurians, who have drugged him (needlessly), 
taken him to a planet orbiting Alpha Centaur i, and put his brain in 
a vat, waring tt to a computer which Is able to replicate precisely the 
brain's being in its old body back in the Haight Chong's 'virtual real- 
it)'' will, by their advanced lechnolo^p be as vivid and complete as 
Cheech's real experience. The wiring completed^ the computer now 
sends Chong's brain the same electrical signals that it would have 
received waking up Lp the sound of his alarm clock. Chong's belief^ we 
finally note, happens to be true, for just as Chong w^akes up, a child 
Alpha Centauriaii has wandered into the lab, carrying Chong^s alarm 
clock, which her father had brought back as a little present. She drops 



74 I*hiiGSf?piiy ofRiiti^kvf w the 21st Century 



the alarm, and U goes off at just the moment that Chong^ ^roggily 

waking up to the computcr-gcncralcd sound of an alarm clock, forms 
tlic belief 'Kiy alarm clock n ringing/ By coincidencp, Chong is thus 
forming a true belief. 

Now though Chong's belief is true^ most of us would intultivety say 
that tn thi^ situation he does not have h^nvkd^^' Ihat his alarm clock is 
ringing. The revealing question is what saying Ihis will incline us lo 
say abouE Checch, waking up hack on earth to ihc real sound of his 
alarm clock ringing. If we say thatChong^s belief is net knowledge, can 
we sLtll affirm that Chccch's belief is kno%vlcdge? Classical internalism 
creates an extremely strong conceptual pressure to answer 'No, we 
cannot affirm this." For internalism holds that the justifiers that make 
true beliefs ^knowledge' must be things to which the believing subject 
has access. But in our scenario, Checch has access to no more or better 
justifiers than docs Chong. Both Cheech and Chong^ after all, have the 
same range and qualiLy of sensations, sensations of waking tJi a room 
to the sound and sight of their familiar alarm clocks. There is nothing 
in his experience to which Cheech can point Lhat is not also available 
to Chong- Tnternalistically, the two are on epistemic par; the internalist 
will thus wani: to treat them identically. Given our initial judgement 
that Chong's '|ustifiers' do not make his belief knowledge, it will then 
strongly seem, if we are classical internalists, that Chcech's justifiers 
cannot make his Ix^Iief knowledge either. 

lixternalism, in contrast, allows oiie to treat the two cases diffcrendy. 
For Cheech's belief is in fact produced by the normal causal process, 
whereas Ciiong^'s is not- Externalists can thus say that Cheech lias 
knowledge while Chong does not, due to some evaluatively relevant 
difference (say, in their objective rdinbiiit}') between the two processes. 
Whether this difference was accessible within the perspective or expe- 
rience of Cheecli or Chong is^ for externalists^ not important: what 
matters is that the difference is actually there. If it is there, then by 
externalist's lights^ Checch^s Lruc bchef can be knowledge though 
Chong's is not. 

Would externalists then see Cheech as lustifled in his l>eUef^ but 
Chong as unjustified? This is a bit tricky. SomeEimes philosophers sim- 
ply stipulate Lliat they will use 'justified' as the technical term for that 
epistcmic additive, whatever it is, that turns true belief into knowledge. 
In that (;vent the answer would be Tes\ liut as Alston and Plantinga 
have taught us, the word ^justification', as used in ordinary English, is 
laden with connotations of doing as one ougliL Externalists do not 
deny that beliefs can be evaluated with respect to this; they insist only 



Stephen} f. Wyt:.^trn 7S 

that this is not what turns true belief into knowledge. Perspicacious 
cxicrnallsis thus give a ticw name for this further thing (warr^intn 
cpLsEemic adequacy, positive epislcmic status, Special KJ, allowing us to 
rclaiii the old terms [rationality^ reasonableness, being justified, and so 
on) for siibjecl "focused dimensions. In any case, externalists are not 
offering an account of what is ordinarily called being justified; they are 
offering an account of sometbing elsc^ and are claiming that it is this 
something else that turns true belief into knowledge, As they see it^ 
Chong^5 belief is just as justified (rational) as Cbeech's belief: it faih to 
be knowledge^ not because it lacks rational justification^ but because it 
lacks iViifTfiiJiL 

But will the two Ik enfitfily unrelated? Here, 1 think, many eKternat- 
isls have gone overboard, Extcrnalism says that what soups a true belief 
up into knowledge is warrant - a relationship of ^positive cj>istemie 
hook"Ujj^ between the knowing subject and the known object. But a 
right-headed extemalism, as I see it, will insist chat this positive epis- 
temic hook-up depends on things gomg sufficiently right at both the 
subject pole and object pole^ not just at the latter. Things going fight 
at the subject pole, especially with respect to howcpistemically mature 
subjects can be expected to perform, given what they have access to, 
are matters of rationality and justification. On a right-headed account^ 
as 1 see it, Chong's being sufficiently rational in his believing will 
remain a necessary condition for his beliefs having warrant; it is just 
not a sufficient condition- 
Sensible evidential Ism 

Let us now return to our question. AH of us are evidentlalists about 
some things, Tite belief in electrons: we intuttivelj' regard electron- 
belief as needing (in a communitarian sense) evidence. But for the Siike 
of ^^'hdt is this needed? We can now propose that it is needed for the 
sake of electron-beliefs having warrant (or Special K). We have Jusl seen 
tltat a belief can lack warrant due to malfunction either at the subieei 
pole (which tj-'plcally involves Irrationality) or at the object pole 
(which need not). If Gretel is a vtctini of the Copenhagen Con^ the 
malfunction arises at the object pole. Gretcl could thus be entirely 
n^tionai m believing in electrons; nevertheless, the evtdentialist (about 
electrons) will want to s<iy that her belief is cpistemically defective 
(it lacks svarrant), due to a dreadful malfunction at the ob|ect pole 
outside her cognitive access. This, I propose, captures with some fidelity 
what our evidentialism about electrons comes to: about electrons, we 



76 fhUo.wpiiy ofRiiti^kvf w the 21st Century 

arc warrant-cvidcntialisEs, not rationality for cnlitlcmcnt-) cvidentialists. 
Rationality-ckadcnLiali^m abotil electrons is, as the case of Gretd helps 
show, a thoroughly extravagant position. [The denial of this position 
i3y accordingtyn ratlicr uninteresting-) But warrant-evidcnLialism about 
electrons i5 not only truer to our intuitions^ Lt is also a lar more sensi- 
ble position- I liereby dub it sensible evidentialism. 

But now let us suppose that theistic cvldcntialists^ all along^ have 
meant to say about belief iti God the same thing that we, all along, have 
meant to say about belief in electrons. They have not been rationality- 
evidentiatists; they have been warrant-evldenlialisls- (Of course they 
have often sounded like rationality-cvidcntialists; but we have sounded 
tlic same way talking about electrons. Thcyn like us^ did not after all have 
the distinctions we now have, between rationality and warrant; so they 
could express their evidentialist intuitions only through a glass darkly.) 
The Reformed epistcmoiogists, in all their brush-clearings have criticized 
only rationalit)''-cvidentlallsm. But they have never, so far as I can sec, 
sought to clarify what cvidentialism about electrons might look like, and 
to ask whether that might be what evidentialists about God arc also 
trying (in their philosophically juvenile way) to say. In this rcs[>:ct, 
Ihcy have indeed treated evidentialism as a polemical partner. 

What is inferential evidence? 

Sensible evidentialism, I have argued, holds lliat l>eliefs which need 
Inferential evidence need it in a communitarian way (not an individu- 
alistic wayln and need it for the sake of warrant {not for the sake of 
rationalitjO. I now turn to one last question: What h this infcrentLal 
evidenced lliat we may need it? Reformed epistemologists, it seems to 
me^ have worked with rather impoverished notions of inferential evi- 
dencCp I shall propose that this is because they^ like the cvidentialisLs 
they criticize, have fallen under the spell of strong foundationalism. 
Taking Reid and extcrnalism seriously^ as they ask to do, should lead us 
to expand our notion of inferential evidence. 

Consider again l^lantinga's 14-yeai-old thcist, brought up to believe 
in God in a community where everyone so believes. He believes what 
people tell him about God^ but, says Plantinga [1981^ p^ 33) he 'does 
not take what people say as evidenced For: 



he docs hot reason thus: everyone around lierc says that God loves 
us and cares for us; most of wliat everyone around here sa)^ is true; 

so probably that's true. 



Stephen} f. Wyt:.^trn 77 

Instcadf he simpiy heiiei'es what he's taught. Plantinga says Hansel siinply 
l>cUcvcs, Mc believes in a basic or iioii-lnfcrcntml way, for, says Plantt- 
nga, he 'doc^ not reason thus'. But what woiiid have to he involved, if 
he were to rca:>on thus, so ihaL his bcHcf would qualify as an inferential 
rather than a basic one? Reformed cpistcmolo^ists, it seems to mc, usu- 
ally suppose that three things would need to be involved: 

(■dl) He must expiicitly and oceurrently believe the propositions that 

constitute his evidence; 
iC2'} He must have some insight or puiaiive insi^^ht into a supporL- 

relation between these OGTurrcntly believed propositions and the 

belief he holds on their basis; 
(C3) This insight or putative insighi must play a significant causal role 

in generating or sustaining S's belief tJiat God exisls. 

Reformed epistemologisls, I believe^ tend to regard Inferential beliefs as 
requiring these conditions. On Cl, consider Plantlnga's recent discus- 
sion of tivo sixth-trader Sj both believing that the earth Is round. One 
of them, we miglit as well keep her as Gretel, believes tliis on the basis 
of evidence, ^[^erhaps she ha5, like Aristotle, noticed how saihiig ships 
drop over the visual horizon on a clear day: judging that this is l>cst 
explained by supposing that the earth is foui:idH she concludes that 
probably, the earth is roundj The either one, let^s keep hini a:s Hansel, 
also believes that the earth is round, but he, in his usual credulous way, 
just trustingly believes what his teacher tells him. Now the beliefs of 
both children^ Plantinga says, may have warrant, but they get this war- 
rant In quite different ways. Grctel's belief B gets warrant by way 'of 
being believed on ihe (evidential) basis' of some other belief, A, and to 
get warrant in this ^'ideiitinl way, she 'mu.^f believe A as well as B'. 
HanscTs belief, In contrast, gets warrant in a dirfcren: testmiomid way, a 
way for whichp Plantinga avers (1993b, p. 138), Hansel 'need wof explic- 
itly believe chat the testifier testifies to what he does'. That thouRhtn 
Plantinga explains, 'may never cross his mind; he may be paying 
attention only to the testimony'. Plantinga's point is that the teacher's 
testimony may occasion Hansel's forming a warranted basic belief that 
the earth is rounds witJiout Hansel ever forming the belief that his 
teacher has told him this_ And in exactly this respect, as 1 read him, 
PLantinga means to contrast Hansers warranted basic belief with 
Greters warranted inferei^thil belief . (An inferenLlal or non-basic belief 
Is one that is held on the evidential basis of other heliefs.) Mansers 
belief is trig^ereit by (or groundeii in) testimony^ not inffrrt'd from it: it 



7R FhiiDXGphy ofR^lfg^ioi! in tSie 2isl Century 

can ihus get warrant from the testimony Vithout any eKplicit belief 

On Maiiscl's part lliat the teacher lias given Ihis leslimoiiy. [n contrast, 
Greters belief gets its warrant evidentiijlty (or inferentially) from B; for 
this to be sOh Grclel, unlike Hansel^ ''must believe R\ 

C2 says that for S's belief to be inferential, S musl have insight or 
putative insight into a supporl- relation between the belief and its evi- 
dential basis. But what is it to take some belief to support (or be good 
evidence for) some other belief? I^asicalists typicall)^ construe this as a 
m^Ltter of having some argument that derives the one Irom the other 
Consider here a slriking passage by Wolterstorff (1987^ p, 76): 

When I survey this gigantic intricate world, I cannot believe that it 
lust came about. I do not mean that 1 have some good arguments 
for its being made and iliat 1 believe in the arguments. I mean that 
this conviction wells up irresistibly within ine when 1 contemplate 
the world. 



Xow of course, Wolterstorff sees his conviction as due to his appre- 
hending certain features of the world; he even specifies, and so has 
explicit beliefs about, wliat these features are. It is, he says, a 'gigantic 
intricate world'; it is (he says a few lines laterl 'full of beauty and splen- 
dor\ and so on. His belief in God thus satisfies CI. Still, he docs not see 
it as inferential, for he does not 'have good arguments^ tliat get him 
from these features of the world to theism. Wolterstorff, for this reasoRj 
lends to think that his theistic conviction is not cvidentiallv or infer- 
entially based on his beliets or apprehcndings regarding the world^s 
intricacy, splendour^ and the like: it is triggered by them, but not infer- 
entially based on ilicm. To be infereiitially based on them would 
require him to have arguments, argument involving some rational 
insight into support-relations between the world's being intricate, full 
of beauty and splendour and so on, and its being made by God. 

Finally, C3. C3 can be illustrated by an example I heard some years 
ago from Plantinga concerning his calculator. Plantlnga believes that 
liii calculator is reliable; he also perceives that his calculator indicates 
funder appropriate digital manipulation) that 1 + 2 = 3. And he takes 
these two things to support, by a good argument, that 1 plus 2 does 
indeed equal 3_ CI and C2 are thus met for his belief that 1+2 = 3. 
Nevertheless^ this belief is basic, not infcrenLial- For his 'calculator 
argument' is, in Robert Audi's terminology^ a reason for wlmt he 
believes [that 1+2 = 3) without being a reason for which he believes 
that 1+2=3. 



Stephen} f. Wyt:.strn 79 



Calvinian£ as strong foundationalists 



Xow there is no doutai, a non-null ^ci of beliefs that have i:lie three 
features just adumbrated. But are these what make a belief 1iiferential7 
That is to say: if we ate going to carve our beliefs into those thai aie 
basic and those that are inferential, are these the features thai should 
guide our carving? 

WeH, what determines whclher a certain way of carving the turkey is 
a good way or not? Classically, whal made 'Lnfercnllallty"" of Inleresl is 
that it is one of those things that can confer, or help to confer, epis- 
Leniic adequacy on a belief. Suppose we go along with this a moment^ 
and refer to a belief as 'properly inferenliar when it gets its knowledge- 
statjs by virtue of being held in some appropriate infLretitUii way. 
(Being 'property Infcrcntiar will ihcn be the counterpart to being 
'properly baslc\ with the proviso that it Is warrant rather than entille- 
ment that we have in mind by the catch-all term 'proper J In asking 
ivhat it takes for a belief to be 'inferential^ then, we will have one eye 
on our conception of what this Special K Is; for our question is really: 
what must inference be, in order to confer on a belief this merit? 

Now the Reformed Eptstemologlsts have been tireless In asserling 
that bcliind evideiiLLahsm lie5 the bankrupt Zeitgeist of strong founda- 
tionalism^ leading to impoverished conceplions of what beliefs can 
be properly basic. When you lift an evidentialist, writes Wolterstorff 
(19&1, p. 142), you almost always Tmd a strong foundationalisL I sug- 
gestj in the same spirit^ that Internailstic strong foundallonalism lies 
behind these overly stringent constraiitts on what can count as prop- 
erly Inferential beliefs. 

In Its slroiigesl formSn internalism holds that a belief-forming process 
can turn a true belief iitto knowledge only if it meets two requirementsr 

(Rl) It must be something to which the subject has privileged access - 

something the presence of which is evident horn within the sub^ 
jecl's perspective. 
^R2l It must be something whose relevance to truth is evident to the 
subjectj so the subject can see that the presence of this feature 
makes a claim worthy of assent. 

These requirements say that positive epistemrc status is conferred only 
by things to whose presence and tiuth-relcvancc ^^respectively) we have 
privileged access. (Here we could also bring in the ideal of acquaintance 
that Wolterstorff has descriliedo Liut these requirements are clearly going 
to generate strictures on what can be believed In a properly inferential 



BO FhUt7^f?piiy ofR^ti^w}! w the 21st Century 

way^ just as they do on what can be bolicvcd in a properly basic way: a 
process can give rise to properly (ihat is, wariaiil-confcmng) inferential 
beliefs only if it meets requirements Rl and R2. And of course, having 
a good argument (conceived along Cartcsian-Lockcan lines) meets 
both requirements nicely. For such arguments rest on lational insi^lil 
inio "^relations of ideas' (that is, into support-relations^ and this is both 
something one can tell from the inside that one has (meeting Rl), and 
something whose relevance to trutli is also evident (meeting R2}. So 
the same internalism that generates ?trong-foundationalist strictures 
iOii the criteria of proper basicality, will also generate these strictures 
(CI, C2 and C3) on criteria of proper infercntialitj^. If a process does 
not meet these conditions, a strong foundationalist will regard it as 
non-inferential (since it is the essence of inferenrtality that it be some- 
tliing that can confer eplstemic adcquac\^ on its products). 

So let^s return to the Woltcrstorff passage with which I began this 
chapter Woltcrstorffs bitter friend asks him 'Why don'^t you just scrap 
this God business?' Woltcrstorff finds thai his conyiction, the convtc- 
tion that God made all this^ wells up irresistibly in him as he surveys 
the world. Reflecting on this convictionj he categorizes it as a basic or 
non-inferential one; he can specify various features of the world giving 
rise to his conviction^ but he does not have good arguments from 
them, to its being so made, liul docs this establish non-intcrentiality? 
It docs, if you suppose that good arguments must involve, and provide, 
rational insight into support-relations - a very natural supposition from 
the internallsrtc perspective of strong foundationalism. On what it 
takes for something to be properly inferential^ 1 thus suggest, when you 
lift a Calvinian, you almost always find a strong foundatianalist. 

IIow externallsiu loustiis the strictures 



But what if one is an externalist instead? I!cre one holds that what 
generates warrant is^ at least in part, soinething like Goldman's 'being 
produced by a reliable process', or like Plantlnga's 'working In accord 
with a design plan m appropriate circumstances'. Being externalist, we 
drop the requirement that something can confer warrant only if the 
believing subject has privileged rcQective access to its presence or 
truth-relevance. Can we not. in this event, drop some of the old stric- 
tures {C1-C3} on proper inferentlality as well? 

To make this suggestion more plausible, consider/ after all^ how we 
evaluate scientific theories. It is widely agreed that given two Incompat- 
ible Ihcories, Tl and 72^ which both fit the empirical data, Tl can be 
more rational to accept on account of Its being more simpie than T2, 



When someone does accept Tl over T2p it sccras clearly to be as a result 

of an inferential process. l^uL at the same tlmc^ It usually rests on a 
simplicity-disposition that is barely consdou?. Give science students a set 
of pressure-volume dala, and ask them to sclccl between several propos- 
als about how the pressure of a gas varies as a functioii of its volume. 
Alniost always, they will judge that the simpler funcUon is more likely 
to Ik true. But in a philosophy of science class, these same sEudents 
will tnitially often dismiss a proposed simplicity criterion with disdain: 
theories, they will say, must be based on obser\'ed facts^ not on some 
wish for siniplLcity. So in practice, they choose^ instinctively as it were, 
in accord with a norm of simplicit^v but they do not, initially at least, 
feel comfortable preaching what they practise. It is only after consider- 
able rencction that they come to articulate awareness and endorsement 
ol" this simpliciLy insUnct in their inferential practices. 

Can the inferential include such ^instinctive' dispositions? 1 believe it 
can. Copernlcus's thcory-preterenee was certainly not a matter of mere 
perception or memory or introspection; it was a conclusion, based in a 
broadly inferential way upon apprehended considerations. As Copernicus 
came to apprehend the simplicity of how heliocentrism explained vari- 
ous data, he found the conviction that the earth orbits the sun w^elling 
up irresistibly within him. He could specify the simple-making featuresj 
caUing the attention of fellow astronomers to them. But he did not 
liavc good arguments from them that would persuade sceptical friends 
like Osiander-argumcntSj that is, providing rational insight - into the 
bearing of simplicity considerations on truth. His con\1ction Avas infer- 
ential; it rested on inferential evidence; but proper inferential! ty (like 
proper basicality) iran involve other dispositions besides the ones 
privileged by strong foundattonalism. IntcrnaUsm makes this difficult to 
swallow, because Gopcrnicus's inference docs not rest on 'rational insighf 
into a support-relation between the simplicity and the verisimilitude of a 
theory- IZxternalism, however, enables us to loosen these strictures on 
inferentiality without compromising the capacity of inference to con- 
tribute to warrant. 

Contluslon 



We thus must broaden our notloti of inferential evidence. Reformed 
Epistcmologists have rightly urged that humans possess a ridi array 
of dispositions producing properly basic beliefs. TEiese dispositions do 
not need to be justified in terms of that disposition providing rationai 
insight of a Cartesian sort^ in order to be worthy of trusty and to confer 
warrant. Sensible Evidentialists here ask that the processes producing 



32 PtsUGSf?piiy ofRiiti^kvf w the 21st Century 

iiiicjr^ntial beliefs get patity of ifoattnGnL The rich complex of inferential 
disposiEionSf every bit as much as the complex of non-lnfercntial ones 
that interacts with it, ultimately requires an epistemoiogy of trust. And 
tliis calls us to bioadlen our criteria of pjoper InfercntialttyH just as we 
broaden our criteria of proper basicality. 

And when we have appropriately broadened it, I tliink it will Lurn 
out that there is more to theisttc evidentialism than Calvinians have 
seen. By this, I do not just mean that when we better understand what 
is inferential, we will be abio to develop better inferential arguments for 
tlieistic beliefs. I mean that wq will he able to discern Inferential con- 
siderations which liave {il! along beer] pfnyhig ttey roles in forming, sus- 
taining, and sliaping the convictions of the theistic community- (This 
would fit what my colleague Stephen Evans (Evans^ 1990), appealing to 
Newsman's account of the 'natural inferences'' that play a role in ordi- 
nary hut mature dieistic conviction^ calls a ''natural theology in a new 
key'-l Paul, tn his Letter to the Romans, says that God has made his 
power and deity evident to us through the things He has made. But 
how does God do this? h secnis to me as^ hicidetitally^ it seemed to 
Thomas Reid, that God does so by designing us so that our cpSstemic 
access to essential theistic truths involves reliance on bromUv infcren- 

r 

Hal considerations. This does not rule out important roles for immedi- 
ate justlflers- Jesus came, Paul says in Ephesians 2:1K, Lhat through him 
we might 1iave access in one Spirit to the Father'- this access in the 
Spirit may well have a non-inferential dimension that contributes 
much to the w^irrant of our beliefs. Sensible evidentialists are grateful 
to Reformed Episteniologists for providing a rightt'ul plnce for these. 
But sensible theistic evidentialists will urge that this experiential com- 
ponent contributes hest, when there is availahle lo the community, 
broadly inferential evidence for other larger theistic claims. For it is 
these lar^^er claims that provide the framework within which we inter- 
pret the Spirit's experiential work in our lives. 



Bibliography 



AlatorLj "VViHiaDii 19S3. 'Christian Experience and Chrlstban Belief, m Ahin 
Piantinga and Nlc]ic3Ja_s Wolterstoifi (edsj^ Fnith luni Rtitiomil^ty: Raut^u imt^ 
Belwfin God, UniveisiEj^ of Notie Dame Press. Notre Dame, IN, 103-34. 

AlstoDj William: 19SHa. 'Religious Diversity and Perceptual Knowledge o^ God', 
Fniitfj amt Pfiih:\opfsy S, 4"-{3^8_ 

Alston, Williami I^SKb, The Pereeplion of God', in MkhaeJ Beatty and Richard 
Lee (eds), Pkitosopkicfi} TbpLs 16, Fall ISBS^ 23-S2, 



Steph^i^ /. tV>-"jt.rtrrt 8:^ 



Alston^ WiiiianiL 1991, Pt^n-eivirj^ Goilj the Epistenfohigy of Religions Experiefice, 

Coinell University Press^ Ithaca^ New York. 
Alston, Wtlliaiii: 19911!^, 'On Kncwing That We Kiioivi the Application to 

Religious Knowtedge', In C- Stephen Evans and Merold Westfala leds)^ Cfiriitiim 

Perspi^ctives an Reiis^iou}^ Kaowiedge, Eerdmans, Grand Rapids, Mi^ 15-39. 
Alston, William: i99jiibr 'Epcstemic DLsiderata^ Fhiiosopfjy msd PlseisomeiiGhgkat 

Reseani} UIl 527-51. 
Audi^ Robert: 1936, 'Direct Justification, Evidential Dependence, and Theistlc 

Belief', in Robeit Audi and William J, Wainwright Cedsf^ Ratio^iatityf Rttigioxts 

Eeii^f and Mom! Comnntjf^efit, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, New York^ 

139^^. 
Clark^ Kelly James: 199<>j Retuni &> RfiLT^wa; i^ Cutiijue of Enl^^^iitami^at EvuientiiiUsiu 

ami a Defense GfRt£isori and Belief in God, Eerdmans, Grand Rapids, Mi- 
Clark, Kelly James (ed.); 199Z, Oisr Knowledge of God, Kliivi-er, Dordrecht, 
Enge3, Mylan Jl: 1992, 'Peisona] and Doxa^tic Justification in i-^pistemolog)^', 

Philo.iopk}€£il Sti^iiies 67, 1:^-^-50- 
Evans^ C. Stephen: 1990^ 'Apologetics in a New Key: Relieving Protestant 

Anxieties o^^er Natural Theologj'-', in William L_ Craig and Mark S. McLeod 

i;eds), Tiw Logic of Ruitio^rai Tiiessni, Edwin MeJIen Press^ Lewiston, NY, 66-75_ 
EvanSj C, Stephen and Merold Westphal (eds): 199J-i^ Chmttaii FcfAp^^tives on 

Reiigiovs Knowledge, Eerdmans^ Grand Rapids, Ml. 
Hasker, WiEliam; 1986. ""On Justifying the Christia]! PracEict", 77;^ Ntrw Schoiusti' 

dsm6(l i:^9-55- 
Hoitengar Dewey: 1991, faitfi und Re^ison froi^r PU\to to Plantiiigi^i ivi Iniyodneiian 

to Refbrmed Epijiteniotogy, SUNY Pres5, Albany. NY_ 
Konyndyk, Kenneth: 19^6^ i-aith and Evidentialism^, in Robert Audi and 

William J. Walnwright "leds^ RnTiamiiity^ Retigioiis. Beikf and Momt Conamtn^i^'nl, 

Cornell University' Press, Ithaca, NY, S2-10B- 
Kretzmann, Noimani 1992j 'Evidence against Evidentialism'. in Kelly James 

Clark (ed.). OurKnowteiig^ofGiki, K3uwer, Dordrecht. 
Mavrodes, George: 19S3^, 'Je^l^a]^J!m and Athens Revisited', in Alvin Ptantinga 

and Nicholas Wolteistoiff (eds)^ Fnith and RatioiujUlyf Reasoi] and Beiiaf ihi Gad, 

Univeritity of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, IN, L92-21S_ 
Mitchell, Basih 197??, The fif:;ti(icatsvn of Ri^iigiGus Bdief, Seahui}^, NY, 
Pappas, George S_: 1979, 'Basing Relations", in GeoFge Pappas ied_], Jitstifjcation 

and Knawttdg^f D_ Reidel^ Dordrecht, 51^;^. 
PhilJips. D-Z_: 1988, Fai^ii tifteiFoand^itiomifisin, Routledge, New York_ 
Plantinga, AEvini I9BJ?, 'Reason and Belief in God', in Alvin Plantinga and 

Nic]ii:JL"i5. Wolter^Eorff <ed5), Fnilff and Rationaiity, University of Notre Dame 

Press, Notre Dame, IN, 16-9^. 
Plantinga, Alvin: 19R6, 'Coherentism and the Evidentialist Objection to 

Belief in God', in Robert Audi and William J_ "Wainwright {eds), i^tiEft^^Jt^J'jtj'f 

Reii,i;ions B^Uef^ and A-IomS CtjniniiUneni, Cornell Universitj" Press^ Ithaca^ NY^ 

L09-29. 
Plantinga, Alvin: 1991, The Prospects for Natural Theology'j in Jamei E_ 

Tcmberlin ledj, Phiiosopiuaii Perspectives 5: Piu!(}sopby of Ri'lss'ioa, 1991, 

Ridge^lew Pubtishing, Atascadera^ Ci^, 2S7-!^16. 
Plantinga^ Mvin: I99^a, Wl^rrcin^: the Currerit I^efxite. O^tford University Press, 

Oxford. 



34 FhiiGsopiiy ofRiiti^w}! w the 21st Century 



Plantinga, Alvin: L99^b, H^n'dFif £m^ Proper Function!, Oxford Universfetj^ Press, 
Oxford- 

rlantinga^ vUvinj ZfKK), Wi^mnitcd Chn!itiiUi Bclkf^ Oxford University Piess, 

Oxford. 
Pojman. Louis: 19:87^ 'Can ReHgaous Belief Be Rational? , in Louis r_ Pojman 

(ed.)r Phila^oi^hy ofRt'iij^wn: tuj Ainlio{o^^\ Wadsworth, BeJmont, CA^ 4S(>-90_ 
Quinn, Phihp L: 1991, 'Epistemk Parity and l^eligious A^gumeTlt^ in James E. 

Tomb^tiilin ^ed,>, Piiih^opSiicnS Pt^rspectives 5: Phi^osopl^y of Rt'ii^iof^^ 1 991, 

Ridgevae^v Publishing, Atascadera, CAj 317-4 L 
Radcllffe^ Elizabeth 5. and Carrj] J. While [edsj: 1993, Fnith ami Fnicticc: Essi\ys on 

fusiif}'Ui^ Reii^ioui Belief, Open CX>un, Chicago, 196-Z07. 
Reid^ ThomasL 1970^ An Inquiry mtt) ti^e Hmmit? Mimi, ed_ Timothy J. Duggan, 

University of Chicago Press, Chica^. 
Reiter, Davidi 1994, 'Enge] on Enternalism and ExternaMsni in Epistemoloj^'^. 
Sennet, James^ 1993, 'Reformed Fpistemology and Epistemic Duty', in Elizabeth 

S_ Radcliffe and Carol j. White {eds-Jr Fnitb ^md Practice: E^i^ays on Jmtif}4ug 

Retigioii.^ E:^ticf, Open Court, Chicago, 196-207. 
:S*vinburne, RJchardi 1979^ The Exisie^sct^ of God, Oxford Universttj' Press, Oxford, 
WUliamSp Clifford: 1994, 'Kieikegaardian Suspicion ami Properly Basse Seliefs"", 

R^lil^mi.'i Stiidie.^ 30, Z61-7. 
Woltersloiff, Nicholas: 193^. 't:an Belief in God Be Rational U It Has No Touti- 

dations?'^ in AWin Plantinj.^a and Nicholas VVolterstorff (eds)> Fiiith anti Rntio- 

nfiHtyr Reaion LUid R^Siefm Goti^ University of Notre Dame Press^ Notre Dame^ 

IN, i:i5^6- 
Woll-erstorff^ Nicholas: 1986^ 'The Migration of the Theistic Arguments: from 

Natural TheoJogy to EvidentJalist Apologt: tics', in Robert Audi and Wi3EEaiTi J- 

Wainwright [eds|i, RiitUm^^lily^ Relspoiis Bdief^ mui Siomi Coumi^tment, CorneU 

University Press, Ithaca, 38-Kl_ 
Wolterstorff. NicboiasL 19S7, Lamtfit fby a Son, EerdTnans^ Grand Rapids, ML 
Wolterstorff, Nicholas: 1988, 'Once More: Evidentialism - This Time^ Social", in 

Michael Eeatty and Richard Lee (eds>, PSniosophicitt Jbpics 16, l-ah 19SB, S:^-74. 
Wolterstorffr Nicholas: 1992^ 'WhaE Reformc^d Epistemology Is Not", Perspectives 7, 

November 1992, 14-16. 

Woherstorff. Nic3io]as: 1999, 'Reformed EJ^stemology- 

Wykstra, Stephen J_: 19K9, 'Toward a Sensible Bvidentialism; on the Notion of 

^Needing Evidence""', in William L_ Rowe and William J. VVainwrighE [edsji, 

0ii\o!vophy of Rellj^ion: Selected Reaifings, second edition, Harcourt Brace 

Jovancmch, New York, pp. 426-37- 
Wykstra, Stephen }.: 1990, 'Reasons, Redemptions, and Realism- the j\Kio3ogic3l 

Roots of Rationality in Science and Religion", in Michael D, Eeaty {ed-}^ Chns- 

dan Thei.vu ami tiit^ Protiems of i'^hiti^Jiopiiy, University of Notre Dame Press, 

Notre Dame, pp- lia-&l, 
Zagzebski, Linda (ed.ji 1993, Riitiondi Failln Cathoiic Renpotis^e.'i to Refonned 

Epfstenwto^', University of Notre Dame Press^ Notre Dame, iN_ 



6 

Voices in Discussion 

az. PhilUps 



G: The cnligiiLcnmcnt ideal was Lhat of a science of religion — a raiional 
religion. Locke and Kant loom large in this context Locke thought that 
every adult must see that bchcf is Faticmally grounded, and that raLlo- 
nal criteria could he used as a critique of extant religion. I'm told this 
ideal continues to shape contemporary German philosophy of lelij^ion. 

RGformcd Epistcmotogy rejects this demand- U rejects the ideal of a 
rationally grounded religion, but docs not reject rationality Something 
does not have to be grounded to be rational. This docs not mean that 
every religious practice is to be acceptKi as it stands. Much in it may 
not be acceptable. But If docsnt need the metaphysical grounding 
provided by Locke and Kant. All this being so^ 1 need lo say more about 
rationahtv. 

We need to distinguish between three stages of Reformed Epistemology. 
Firsts the papers which belong to the 1970s. Second, the publicafioTt of 
Fiiith and Ration{i!ity in l98.'iE where the former arguments are given a 
more articulate form^ now influenced by Thomas Reid. The emphasis 
was mainly negaLivCj showing what Reformed Epistemology^ denied. I: is 
in a Dutch neo-Calvinist tradition. Its aim is not, like Augustine, to 
understand a faith already given^ but to work out a view of all things in 
the ll^ht of fatth. Clement of Alexandria would be an example of such an 
endeavour. Thirds after l^ti^i the emphasis is more positive: on warrant 
and fustification; appltcation of these to particular features of human life; 
and the bearing of one's religious commitments on one's intellectual and 
non-intclIectual life. It has ne\'er been the aim of Reformed Epistemology 
to give a general account of religion or religious practices. Critics have 
thought that it wanted to do more, but this is not so. 

I ended my paper by trying to pinpoint the differences between 
Reformed Epistcniotog)' and Wittgcnstcinianism in the philosophy of 



&& 



B6 fhiio.wpiiy ofRiiti^kvi w the 21st Century 



idigion. The latter seems to deny that 'God' is a refening expression, 

Qiat there is a 'something' which this word picks out. Bowsma was an 
exception to this. I sometimes hear echoes of Kant in this vieiA^- some- 
times 1 hear an insistence that one can only refer to what one can 
point to; but i really don't understand why VVitlgcnsteinians deny that 
we can refer to Gcid_ 

}^: Reformed cpistemology is to Calvin College what logical positivism 
is to Vienna. I feci like a country priest asked to criticize the pope, litit 
Tve been an evldenlialist since the age of fourteen. I think that the e^'i- 
dentialisl Reformed Epistemolo^^ attacks is a straw man. When I looked 
at the stars I thouj^hl that the question of whether Gtxi had created 
them could go cither way. Why must Faiionality shun e\^tdenEiaIism by 
saylngp with Platitinga^ that it all depends on what you regard as 'prop- 
eriy basic7 Plancin^a uses 'evidence"" in the narrow^ sense of Lnfcrcntial 
evidence- Reformed cpislemologists say that when you look at a daisy, 
or^ better, a tullp^ you find welling up inside you the thought that God 
is present. Similarly when one is told that God was rcconcilin;^ the 
world to himself in Jesus Christ. These basic tendencies are innocent 
until proved guilty^ so we can go along with these doxastic practices. 
That's Calvinism. 

But I think evidence is needed if I am asked to believe that matter is 
composed of protons, neutrons and electrons- Other beliefs^ such as 
1 have two hands' are not believed on evidence. What about religious 
belief? Does it need evidence in Plantinga^s narrow sense? 

I agree thai wc need to get beyond the first two negative stages of 
Rcfomicd Eptstemolog^'^ to a consideration of warrant and fustification. 
So what is it for a hcliet' to be rational? Rationality is a many splen-^ 
'<k»i^d thing, but to be irrational is to be culpable; it Is not doing your 
duty by the evidence. Reformed epistemologists rightly reject inferential 
evidence, for belief in God is basic. It can be reasonable to believe that 
God exists. So rattona! belief does not entail evidence. Tlie same is true 
in science where we choose to believe our teachers. We can sec that the 
claims need evidence^ but we need not have gathered it ourselves- 

The notion of warrant helps us to capture these complexittes- It oper- 
ates at a subject pole. To be warranted at the object pole, things must 
be as the belief claims. But this warranting need not be something 
actually done at the subject pole. Vet, someone in the community must 
have done so. The need for evidence, then, is not that of a specific 
individual^ but that of a community If wc think of evidence in this 
way different types of evidence must be brotight in. 



D^. rhfilips B7 



D: Since G has devoted a considerable amount of space to his disagree- 

menEs with Q Vm. going to ask C to reply. 

Cr First, 1 want to comment on G's claim that 1 have misunderstood 
Plantin^a_ G claims that when you Lift an evidentialisi you fmd a strong 
foundationalisL N lespoiids that when you lift a Calviniaii you almost 
always find a strong foundationalisc. Was Plantinga an exception? Not 
oil my reading of Fnith ^vid Ratioiiaiity and the early discussions of it in 
The Reformat JonmaL ft is clear in thcni that the relation of Ftcformed 
EpLstemologif^ to foundational ism was a central issue; especially the 
claim that there arc only two kinds of foundational propositions^ the 
sclf-c\'Ldcnt propositions of lo^c and mathcmatLeSp and the proposi- 
tions concerning incorrigible sense experiences. Plantinga argtjed that 
since there is no adequate criterion for proper basicality, thcists should 
not accept this restriction. The proposttion that there are only i\wo 
kinds of foundational propositions, he argued, is not itself a self- 
evident pioposition. Thus, although a believer cannot demonstrate to 
an unhelicvcr why he should place belief in God In the foundations of 
his noetic structure, the latter has no good logicat reason to prevent 
the believer from doing so. Reacting to this In The Reformed Joumai, 
Jesse de Boer said: 'While Plantinga protests that foundationalistn 
ought to be abandoned, w4iat he in fact does hlirLself Is to add to the 
foundations our belief in God. He calls this belief ^properly basic' and 
so, by the sense of his own idiom, he stays Inside the foundationalist 
camp/ G denies this, but de liocr's Lind of point led to distinctions 
being made belwccn classical foundationalistn - the view that there are 
only two kinds of fotindational pTojxjsittons - and foundationalism. 

G argues that the idiom of 'proper basicallty^ must not be used to 
mean "foundaiiions'- Plantinga did not take this advice. Here he Is in the 
batde for foundations: 'On this view every noetic structure has a founda- 
tion; and a propositioii is rational for S^ or known by S, only if it stands 
in the appropriate relati ons to the ioundation s of S's noetic 
stnjcture.,- Might it not be that my Ix^licf in God is itself in the foun- 
dations of my noetic structure? Perhaps it is a member of F, in which 
case, of course. It will automatically be evident with respect to G/ 
Again, here is Plantinga responding to a classical foundationalist: ^He 
means to commit himself to reason and to nothing more - belief in 
God, for example - in its foundations. But here there is no reason for 
the theist to follow his example; the believer is not obliged to take his 
word for it. So far we have found no reason at all for excluding belief 
In God from the foundations/ 



B8 fhUo.wpiiy ofR^ti^w}! w the 21st Century 



No doubt Reformed Epistcmology has now gone in somewhat different 

directions. G says that by 'basic belief Plantlnga means what he means 
by ^tTnmediate belief. Perhaps - and here I speculate, G was always less 
enamoured with lelalioiis hclween 'immediate belief" and 'foundational 
baslcalir^'" than l^tantingan in wliich case his present comments could be 
seen as an exercise in damage limitation in this area. 

G gives the impression that ray criticisms depend entirely on the 
issue of foundations. This is not so. I spend an equal amount of lime 
criticizing the notion of ^immediate belief and its relation to authentic- 
ity, I criticize, on grounds of logic^ the fatal slide from the fact that an 
individual need not, in fact, check the authenticity of an experience, to 
the claim that the experience is self-authenticating. Plantinga conflates 
psychological and logical considerations, as when he claims that the 
self-cvidcticc of tnathcmatical propositions must be relativized to 
persons. Wlicther an individual grasps a mathematical proposition 
docs not affect its logical status as a proposition - that ts determined by 
the arilhraetical system. No matter what mathematical intuitions one 
may have one must still pass the ej^amination. No matter what religious 
intuitions one may have, the spirits are tested to see whether they are 
of God in the wider rchgious practice. There are differences between 
these cases, and no doubt between them and examples discussed in On 
Gertninty, but they do net affect the logical point at issue. All these 
points and quotations are made in Fdith after Foitmiationatism, and T am 
disappointed that G does not address them. 

Second, a w^ord about G's conception of the issue between Reformed 
Epistemolog)^ and WittgcnsLcinianism: the question of whether 'there 
is any such phenomenon as referrift^ to God'. He sa);^ that I deny this 
and hold that there is nothing we can predicate of God for the simple 
reason 'that there^s no such being as God to refer to'. Hence the cliarge 
il^at 1 give an atheistic account of religious language. G says that he 
could cite passage after passage to support this view, but thinks it 
otiose to do so for an audience such as this, whereas^ ironically, / says 
that 1 have pointed out the misunderstandings of claims like G's 'so 
often and so forcefully that it would seem entirely otiose even to raise 
the question again, if it were not for the fact that these rebuttals have 
been so singularly unsuccessful in achieving their aim'. Why should 
this be so? Because readers like G prefer to construct general theses and 
propositions than pay attei^tion to the detailed grammatical analyses 
which have been offered by, for example, Rush Rhces, Peter Winch 
and mysclL It is only by ignoring ttiese analyses and examples that G 
can accuse me of l?cing 'remarkably chary of telling us why there 



DJ[. Hlfilips B9 



cannot be any such phenomenon as referring to God\ So let mc 
remind him of some- 

Rush Rhees brings out the difference between talking about a human 
being and talking about God. I may know VVin5ton Churchill vsilhout 
knowing that he is Prime Minister or a company director. 1 can point 
to the iT of which these ihings are true - thai cliap over there. But, 
Rhees says, 1 could not know God without knowing that he was Cre- 
ator and Father of all things. That would be Hke saying thaL I might 
come to know Winston Churchill without knowing that he had face, 
hands, body, voice or any of the attributes of a human being/ There is 
an internal relation then between love, grace, majesty, and so forth, 
and God's reality. It is not that these belong to a further something, a 
thing, as in the case of a human being, but that these uses of 'love', 
'grace' and 'majesty' are themselves the conceptual parameters of the 
kind of reality God has - God is divinely real, fj is wrong in thinknig 
that O.K. Bouwsma does not concur with this view. Bouwsma points 
out how we can be misled by the indicative form of certaiti sentences 
such as 'Great is Jehovah^ 7*^'^°^'^^ reigneth', into thinking that 
they are bits of information, descriptions of an object called 'God', 
whereas other sentences^ such as, 'Bless Jehovah, O niy soul', by their 
imperative form, help us to avoid that misunderstanding. He asks 
whether 'High is our God above all gods' is to be understood as 'fligh 
is the Empire State Building above all other buildings in New York' 
and, looking at the state of philosophy of religion replied sadly, Tm 
afraid so/ 

G thinks that 1 would go to the death rather than use the word 'refer' 
in relation to God, On manv occasions I have said that this is not so. 
Witli iUiees I have said that if not using it leads to trouble, if it leads to 
the view that talking about God doesn^t mean anything, or if it leads G 
to think I hotd tliat all religious language is metaphorical - a view 
I ar^e against In the last chapter of Faith after Fotmd{itionafi5nf - or more 
surrealislically, if he thinks that I have reduced 'God' to an exclamation - 
then by all means keep the word 'refer'. Only, don't think you have 
achieved any clarificatory work hy simply putting the wotd in italics. 
Consider: 1 have a hole in my heart', 'I have palpitations in my heart', 'I 
liave God in my heart.' By all means say that something is referred to in 
aU these cases, but it is not the word 'something' or ^reference' which 
gives sense to these expressions, but the uses of these expressions, includ- 
ing the uses of 'in my heart', which illuminate the grammar of 'some- 
tliing' and 'reference' in these contexts- Donl fight over lalx:ls - look at 
their use. 



90 FtsUosGpiiy ofR^ti^kvi w the 21st Century 



A final paragraph about ihc nature of philosophy. Wittgenstein 
stands in a coiilcmplatlvc tradition which goes back lo Plato. As N 
5ays, G's tradition offers, not a philosophy of relt^ion, but a religious 
philosophy. G says that his cask is not that of seeking to understand a 
faiili already givcnn but to develop history, sociology, philosophy, 
poUtLcal theory, and so forth, in the iLjL^ht of faiths The nature of phi- 
losopliy is itself a philosophical problem and much of its history has 
been spent discussing it. In Wittgenstein, wc see a supreme example of 
an attempt to teach us differences born of philosophical wonder at the 
world in all its variety - the city with no main road. Thus it raises the 
question oi what it is to sec all things religiously; whether that perspec- 
tive is a theoretical matter. It would want to see what other perspec- 
tives look Itkc and what disagreement between them amounts to. It 
would deny that philosophy underwrites any of these perspectives. It 
seems that in Reformed Epistemology all subjects are the handmaid of 
faith which has the final say. By contrast^ from a contemplative tradi- 
tion Wittgenstein says: ^A philosopher is not a citizen of any commu- 
nity of Ideas. That^s what makes him a philosopher."" 

F: I take G's point that belief can be shaped by tradition, but can there 

be competing basic beliefs? Nietzsche looked at the sky and concluded 
that the whole is a great cosmic stupidity. The universe doesn't even 
know we are here. Flow^ do we solve these conflicts? 

G: F is wary of leligious authority^ How do you see a person by religious 

authority? This is where Rcld on perception came to my aid. For 
Descartes and Locke you begin with sensations and then infer the exis- 
tence of the external world. For themn perception is reasoning by infer- 
ence. Reid says that our sensations carry information about the 
external world. We are so 'hard-wired' that we form beliefs on the basis 
of these sensations, but that there is no process of reasoning which 
enables yotj to do this. We are so constructed that we trust our beliefs- 
There is no non-circular argument for doing so. 

So Reformed Epistemology says that a rcligtous perception of reality, 
if things are working properly^ would form an idea of God. Whether we 
can find good arguments for this would be an interesting qucstj as in 
the case of sensations and the external world, but they can't make the 
transition in themselves- Now^ N says, 'No. The proper analog)^ is not 
bcCw-een religious belief and Retdian perception^ but between religious 
iKlicf and explanation In science/ 

If we take the Reidian conception our beliefs will be due to our 'hard- 
wiring' and to wiiich concepts are available to us. The concept of a 



uj:. Hifilips 91 



computer may not be available lo a tribe. So cvcr)'lhiiig depends 

which conccDis set formed. 



oti 



/: You say that basic beliefs are non-inferential, but how arc they 
formed? What mediating factors make them possihle? How do we 
choose our basic beliefs? Aie basic beliefs frozen for all time? 

G: There are many modes of media Hon, so no general talk ml] do. We 
have to get away from the paradigmaUc distinction between mediate 
and immediate knowledge found in Locke. The use of warrant can 
appeal to a variety of iHLedialions which get us away from thinking of 
the foundational aspect, th response to C's earlier comments I will 
admil that Plantinga is reluctant to come straight out and admit that 
this constitutes a change. 

O: How docs the appeal to authority get going? Is there a necessary link 
between Reformed Epistemology and the function of authority? 

N: Tliis depends on what claims are being made_ I would never have 
re-entered the Christian fold if I had simply been told to accept an 
authority^ for example, if I had simply been told, ^Read the scriptures 
and wait lor conviction/ 1 needed to read RD. Urucc and the opinion 
of other scholars about Biblical documents- Ciaims sometimes depend 
on their work. 

O: Does that apply to ^God exists'? 

jV: a believer may have an inchoate sense of the evidence, in which 
case philosophers tike Swinburne can be of hcip. 

G: But what is being appealed to here seems to be a hlcnd of phiLosoh' 
phy and theology. Tt is essential to Reformed Epistemology that the 
assessment of beliefs is carried on in the context of a livitig faith. If you 
don't accept this you will be attracted to a position like Ai's. But if N 
thinks that the fteidian view of perception is correct, why not apply it 
to religion? 

F. But what docs a child know of this inner community which recog- 
nizes the need for grace? Isn't this a dogmatic, insular view which 
doesn't recognize the child^'s situation^ or the various traditions of dif- 
ferent countries? Reformed Epistemology seems insuJar. 

N: I think you're right. The believer needs to be convinced not only at 
the subject pole, but also at the object pole. He must listen to what 
experts say about how things are. 



92 FhUt7^f?piiy ofR^ti^w}! w the 21st Century 



Q: For sophisticated people, it is claimed^ it won^t be enough to say ^He 
lives In my heart/ But doesn't a lot depend on that? What would a 
neutral assessment of the evidence be like? 

R: Well, It's not enough for a belief to be merely In the ak A testimonial 
claim can be as strong as its weakest link and indefinitely long. Some 
claims go back to Christ. Don't we get a strong groundiiig for these in 
tl^e community? 

G: Fm not sure where W stands. At first he stresses the need for evi- 
dence. But then he says that the iiifcrcncc can be highly intuitive and 
need not be laid out by anyone. That would bring it close to unre- 
formed canonical Reformed Cpistcmology. But then N adds that this 
highly intuitive inference must be spelled out by someone in the com- 
muiitty. But N would not make this added requirement in the case of 
perception. 

in conclusion, let me return to issues raised by Wittgensteinianism 
and respond to (r's earlier comments. Take a phrase like Tathcr of all 
^hings^ If C is prepared to say that this 'picks out something^ to which 
i can relate my hopes and disappointments^ there is no dispute 
betTAxen us. 

H: But wh^t if it said that sentences in Christian beliefs are not asser- 
tions, but performative utterances. How does that affect their truth? 

G: They may be performative or relalional, 1>ill tiiey are still statements 
that address something- In 'Bless the Lord O my soul', the Lord is still 
picked out. 

C: But so far we have said nothing about the grammar of either 'some- 
thing' or 'pick out"" in this context. 

G: Agreed. That is the point at v%^hich a detailed future discussion 
betuTen us would need to begin. 



Part III 

Wittgenstein and 
Wittgensteinianism 



7 

Wittgenstein and the Philosophy 
of Religion 

Stephen Mulh^ll 



Wittgerislcinian approaches lo issues in the philosophy of tdi^ion have 
plainly been amongst Ehe most consequential in the discipline in the 
postwar period. This is nol, of course^ because a general consensus in 
their favour has been established; on the contrary if anything unites 
contemporary philosophers ol: rclajjionn it is their deep suspicion of both 
the specific claims and the general methodology^ of those of their col- 
leagues who have adopted a W'lltgcnsteinian perspective. Nevertheless. 
it is rare to find a philosopher of religion who docs not define her own 
position, at least in part^ by specifying the nature of and ihe grounds 
for her rejection of w^ork carried out under the Wittgcnstciiiian banner 
In this respect, that work conthiues to function as an essential refer- 
ence point in the discipline - something that can no longer be said of 
many other fields of philosophical endeavour, even in the philosophy 
of mEiid or the philosophy of language fwhcri! some of Wfttgcnstein's 
specific claims continue to attract interesE, but the general method- 
ological principles which anchor and account for them are barely men- 
tioned^ let alone specifically criticized). 

Those better apprised of the radical subversion to which Wittgenstein 
aimed to subject the discipline of philosophy can hardly be surprised at 
the suspicion in which Wittgenstein ian approaches to religion are held; 
but they are bound to Ix^ intrigued by the way in which philosophers of 
rclij^ion seem far less capable than Lhcir colleagues ht cognate fields of 
simply leaving those approaches behind - of treating their own suspi- 
cions as adequate grounds for dismissing Wittgenstcinian approaches 
ratlicr than as endlessly renewed incentives to rcnzxamine them. It is 
almost as if these approaches go with the territory - as if this perspec- 
tive on the philosophy of religion resonates so intimately witli some 
barely registered but fundamental aspect of the domain of rchgion itself 



95 



96 fhUosGpiiy ofR^ti^kvf w the 21st Century 

that those fascinated by the latter naturally find themselves unable 

deflnlEivcly to dismiss the former. 

I-s this scn^e of paradox intensified or dissipated if we further note 
that VViLtgen stein's own remarks on the philasophy of rclif^ion are van- 
ishingly slight in comparison with the sheer mass of his remarks on the 
philosophy of mind or of language? Should we conclude that philoso- 
phers somehow find it easier to get beyond the former than to dismiss 
the latter entirely easier as tt were to stumble over a few scattered peb- 
bles than to vauH over a mountain range? Or should we rather recog- 
nize that the very paucity of Wittgenstein's owit remarks makes theni 
difficult to construe and hence eas^^ to misconstr je? Seen in this light, 
it may seem that what so many philosophers of religion stumble over is 
not so much Wittgenstein's few pebbles but the complex and ramified 
edifice that has been constructed from them; it may be that what they 
find ob|ectionablc is not Wittgenstein but w^hat Wittgensteinians have 
made of him. These opening Impressions suggest a tripartite structure 
for the ensuing discussion. 1 shall begin by examining Wittgenstein's 
own remarks on the philosophy of religion; then I shall look at the dis- 
tinctive characteristics of Wittgensteinian approaches to this area; and J 
shall conclude by raising some questions about what one might call a 
religious interpretation of Wittgcnstcin^s general approach to philoso- 
phy - about how one inight attempt to accoui:Lt for the spiritual fcrv^our 
that so many have sensed in his ^vritings- 

Wittgenstein's interpretation of religion 



In attempting to elucidate Wttgenstem's philosophical view of religion 
and religious belief, "^-vc must bear in mind not only that his recorded 
expressions of those views are very small in number but also that few 
of them were recorded by him and none were originally intended for 

publication (our sources consist of 20 pages of his students' lecture notes^ 
and a scattering of remarks in such miscellanies as Cuiture ami Value^ 
and Recollixtions of WittgemtemJf hi other words^ even these apparently 
direct expressions of his \aGws arc in reality multiply filtered through 
the memories^ editorial proclt^ltics and linguistic sensibilities of others; 
even hcrc^ separating Wittgenstein from the VVitlgenstcinians is far from 
simple. 

The most systematically developed of these remarks (which is not to 
say that they are very systematically developed) are presented in the 
notes made of three 1938 lectures. Broadly speaking, the first lecture 
emphasizes important diffecences bctA'vecn religious beliefs aitd Ijctiefs 



about maltcrs of fact fhistorical and empirical inaltcrs}? the second 
emphasizes parallel differences between a belief in God's existence and a 
bf^licf in the existence of a person or object; and the third explores the 
significance of a belief in life after deaths or in the immortality of the 
soul- In all three cases, Wittgenstcm engages in a gtaminatical investiga- 
tion of these topics: he attempts to clarify the nature of religious [>clief by 
c^^rifyin^ the use of expressions of religious belief - the place of religious 
concepts and religious uses of concepts in the lives of believers and 
un believe rs- 

Wbat he claims to establish thereby ;jrows from one fuiidaineiital 
insight - the fact that those svho hold to religious doctrines do not 
treat those commitments in Uie way they would treat an empirical 
claim. ITiey do not regard ihcm as hypotheses wliosc credibility s'aries 
in accordance w-ith the strength of the evidence in their favour they 
do not assign them degrees of probability^ and so on. Even ivith what 
appear to be historical religious propositions ^for example^ concerning 
Christ's existence and life on earth), says Wittgenstein, believers do not 
treat them as they do other historical propositions. His point ts not ]ust 
that a believer's conviction in their truth appears utterly insensitive to 
the kinds of ground for donbt and caution that she would apply to 
other propositions about the dim and distant past. It is rather that, 
even if propositions about Christ's life in Palestine were established 
beyond all reasonahle doubt in just the way tliat (for example) some 
facts about Napoleon ^s life have been established, this kind of certainty 
would not have the practical consequences in our lives that a religious 
belief has. As Wittgenstein puts it: 'the indubi lability wouldn't be 
enough to make mc change my whole life' tLC, p. 57). 

In other words^ the divergence between the role played In our lives 
by religious beliefs and by empifical beliefs is so systematic and pcrt^a- 
sive that Lticy must be acknowledged to be very different kinds of 
behcf. We would otherwise be forced to the conclusion that rehgious 
believers generally act in a manner so ludicrously irrational as to strain 
credibility: as blunders go, this would just be too big - certainly too big 
to attribute to people who don't after all treat weather forecasts in the 
way tliey treat Gospel warnings about the Last Judgement. Neither, on 
the other hand^ would we want to say that religious beliefs ate 
obviously rational, as if it is obviously unreasonable ro reject what faith 
demands. Religious believeis base matters of great moment on evidence 
that seems exceedingly flimsy by comparison with the corroboration 
they require before accepting claims of far less significance for their 
lives; and 'anyone who reads the Epistles will find it said: not only that 



98 fhUo.wpiiy ofRiiti^kvf w the 21st Century 



it is not reasonable but that tt Is folly. Not only is it not reasonable^ but 

it doesn't pretend to be' \LC, p. 58). It is rather that the evidence for 
religious beliefSp the doubts to which they may be subject and the cer- 
tainty they may command are not species of empirical evidence, doubt 
and certainty. '[Religious) controversies took quite different from any 
notmal controversies. Reasons look entirely different from normal 
reasons' (LC^ p. 56). From this contention^ everything else Wittgcti- 
stein s*iys in these lectures can be derived. His claim that the religious 
hclievGr and the atheist cannot be said to contradict one another !n the 
mancier of disputants over an empirical claim^ and his observation that 
a belief in the ejtistence of God plays a role entirely uiilike that of a 
belief in the existence of any person or object he has ever heard of 
(buttressed by pointing out that^ for example^ our ways of employing 
pictures of God do not include any technique of comparing the picture 
to that which it depicts}^ simply reiterate at a more concrete level his 
general claim about the difference between religious [>eliefs and empir- 
ical ones. And his discussion of the role played by a belief in life after 
death proceeds on the assumption that this is not an empirical hypotlv 
esis about the relation of minds to bodies, and asks how such a claim 
might play a role in the lives of tliosc who make it^ he suggests that 
this role would be clarified if, for example^ the believer connects the 
idea to certain notions of ethical responsSbillty (for example, by relat- 
ing the sours immortality to tlie idea of its being subject to judge- 
ment). Here Wittgenstein attempts to locate one religious concept In a 
grammatical network of other such concepts, and to locate that net- 
work in llie context of a certain way of living - thus returning us to 
tlie opening theme of his first lecture in a manner that should surprise 
no-one familiar with his general methodological claim that 'to imagine 
a lan^age is to imagine a form of life'. 

Most of the remarks about religion scattered through the miscellanies 
I mentioned earlier could also be seen simply as developiiig this same 
fundamental point about ihe divergences bet^veen religious and empiri- 
cal beliefs. This is particularly evident mth respect to nvo remarks from 
Culture ami VaiuL' that have attracted particular attention: God's essence 
is supposed to guarantee his existence -what this really means is that 
what is here at issue is not the existence of something (CV, p. HI). It 
strikes me that a religious belief could only he something like a pas- 
sioi:iate commitment to a sj^tem of reference (CV, p. 64). 

As the sentences immediately following the former remark make 
clear, Wittgenstein is not denying that a belief in God^s existence is a 
belief in the existence of something but rather that it is a belief En the 



3ti^pfieii Mit!haif 99 



existence of some thing; he isdcnyin;R;tha: God^s existence is akin to the 
existence of a while cicphaiil, of 3 physical ol^ject or entUy - specifically 
in the sense that God (like the white elephant) might not have existed, 
that the grammar of the concept of '"God' is such as to allow us to talk 
of 'what it would be like it there were (or if there were not} such a 
thing as "God'^'_ As for the latter remark, it merely encapsulates 
Wittgenstein ^s claims in the lecture that religious believers orient their 
existence as a wiiolc by reference to what he calls 'pictures' - specific^ 
interrelated ways of interpreting and responding to the events and 
experiences that make up their lives, ways that can only be understood 
and explained in terms of religious concepts. 

Strangely^ however^ mucli of the criticism directed at Wittgenstein's 
views on religion has been focused on these remarks rather than upon 
the more detailed and systematic Iceture notes from which they derive; 
and that criticism has depended for its plausibility upon ignoring their 
roots In lliat material^ as well as their more [mmcdiate contexts. For 
example, John H^mian, the author of the entry on 'Wittgcnsteinianism' 
(which is in fact an entry exclusively on Wittgenstein) in the recent 
BSnckwt^ff CompiViion to the PhUosophy of ReUgiou,^ finds both remarks 
impossible to accept.^ The former, he claims, is not supported either by 
the disanalogy between Tiod exists' and existential propositions in 
science or hisiory or geography, or by the doctrine that God cannot 
begin or cease to exist. ""If Democritus believed that atoms cannot 
begin or cease to exist, it does not follow that he did not believe that 
an atom is '^einc Existenz"" - an entity; or something which exists' 
(IWM, p. 261)- 

The difficulty with this argument is its extreme compression^ or rather 
its apparent assumption that we can tell what exactly Democritus's 
beliefs about atoms amount to without far more information about 
tlieir ImpUcattons. In the first place, docs his l>elief that atoms can 
neither begin nor cease to exist amount to a belief in their eternal 
existence or a belief in their endless duration (to employ a distinction 
of Norman Malcolm's, overlooked by Hyman despite his favourable 
citation of some of Malcolm's other remarks in the same cisayj? 
A physical object or object-constituent might come into being at the 
beginning oi the universe and remain in existence until its end; but Us 
non-existence would remain conceivable, and hence Its endless dura- 
tion would be no iess contingent than that of a particular white 
elephant. God's existence, by contrast fas a Kierkcgaardian remark also 
quoted by Hyman asseils), is eternal: his existence is not just unending 
but necessary. Until we know which of these conceptions of atomic 



100 Flrihiwphy of fif/;sTi^?r p;i the 21 it Century 



existence Democritus favours^ we cannot assess its validity as a counter- 
"iexampic, since aii endlessly enduring atom would deserve the epithel 
'eine Existenz' as Wittgenstein deploys it in a way that an eternal atom 
would not. 

Second, even if Democritus does turn out to believe that atoms have 
eternal existence, whilst still being inclined to call both atoms and white 
elephants 'existent things'", this would not show that the kind of exis-^ 
lencc possessed by empirical Uitngs and that possessed by elernal beings 
was identical. On the contrary- the fact that Democritus conceives of 
atoms in such a way as to exclude cerlain possibilities that he leaves 
open with respect to elephants (and vice versa) precisely implies that 
ihe kind of existence he attributes to the former is very different from 
that which he attributes to the latter. Whether or not he (or we) would 
want to call both 'entities' or 'existent things' is entirely irrelevant; 
what malters is not our inclination to use the same phrase in both con-^ 
texts when we give expression to our belief s^ but w^hether or not we 
put it to the same kind of use. 

Hyman's objections to the second remark culled from Culture and 
VaUi^ arc equally unsound. ...I see no reason to accept that coming to 
believe that God exists is nothing taut coining to feet 'a passionate com- 
mitment to a system of reference' - that is, coming to feel committed to 
leading a life in which questions will be asked, obligations will be 
acknowledged, decisions taken and actions performed, which can only 
be explained or understood by the use of religious concepts. For surely. 
If a convert makes that commitment, perhaps because he feels com- 
pelled to, bis belief that God exists will tj^ically be part of his reason for 
dotn^ so. Nothing in Wittgenstein's later philosophy^ and in particular 
no part of his doctrine about the relation between language and forms of 
life, implies that a form of life cannot involve historical or metaphysical 
beliefs (such as that Jesus rose from the dead or that the soul is Immor- 
tall as well as concepts and attitudes: all of them - beliefs, concepts and 
attitudes - in a mutually supporting relation {IWM, p. 260). 

Note to begin with that Wittgenstein does not claim that coming to 
believe that God exists is nothiag but a passionate commitment to a 
system of reference; he claims that 'a religious belief could only be 
something like such a commitment- One might legitimately question 
Wittgenstein's impHcation that there is only one possible way of 
understanding or living out a religious life, but to say that 'x is some- 
thing like y' is plainly not equivalent to saying that 'x is nothing but y\ 
Furthermore, to equate a belief in God's existence with religious belief 
per s^ makes sense only on the assumption that a religious belief or 



Stephen S4iiih^{f lai 



rcli^ous faith is nothing but feilhcr reducible to oi founded upon) a 
bdicf in the existence of God - as if adopiing a religious form of life Is 
a secondary consequence of a lo^cally prior and logically independent 
existential belief. And indeed^ just such a model is presupposed by the 
objection Hynian then goes on to make to Wittgenstein's claim: he 
asserts that a belief in God'^ exislence is typically one's reason for com- 
mitting oneself to a religious frame of reference. 

But this assertion takes it for granted that we know ivhat such a 
belief amounts to or signifies - what the claim to believe that God 
exists (or more plausibly^ the claim to believe In God) actually means. 
And on Wittgenstein's vici^^ we can only establish this by determining 
how the concept of God functions in the practice and life of a leligious 
believer, which means investigating the grammatical connections 
between this concept and the multitude of other religious concepts in 
terms of which a l>cliever interprets the events and experiences of her life. 
But ifj according to this approach, no-one can so much as understand 
what a belief in God's existence amounts to without grasping the IcHza- 
tion of that concept in the grammatical iietwork of religious concepts 
that Wittgenstein here describes as a sj^tcm of reference, it makes no 
sense to think that one can first establish the truth of that belief and 
then use it as a reason for adopting the s)'stcni of reference. On the 
contrary^ one could nol acquire a belief in God's existence without 
both understanding and committing oneself to the broader grammati- 
cal system m which the concept of God has its life. Consequently^ 
Hyman's objection to Wittgenstein's remark simply begs the question 
against Wittgenstein s whole approach - not only to the philosophy of 
rc!lj;"ion but to philosophy in general. 

It is worth noting that Hyman is also wrong to imply that this 
approach entails eliminating either the specific belief in God's existence 
or the very Idea of religious belief more generally from our conception 
of what goes to make up a religious way of life- On the contrary, his 
claim that religious faith involves a mutually suppoiling relation of 
beliefs, concepts and attitudes is perfectly consistent with Wittgenstein's 
position. For first, claiming that the concept of God forms part of 
a system of religious concepts does not entail reducing that coiicept 
to the other concepts to whicJi it is related^ any more than noting the 
grammatical relations between psychological concepts and concepts 
of behaviour entails reducing the concept of pain to dial of pain- 
behaviour; the concepts arc internally related, not synonymous. 
Neitlicr does VVittgenstcin^s einphasis on the system of religious concepts 
entail denying that religious faith involves a multitude of specific l?ctiefs; 



102 Flrihiwptiy ofReiisfou m the 21 it Century 



on the contrar)^, that system of concepts is what makes it possible for 
believers to give expression lo ihcir beliefs, and it is in part through thai 
s]i^tem and the linguistic expressions it makes possible that reHgious atti- 
tudes make themselves manifest. Wliethcr we want to say with Hymaii 
that such religious beliefs are 'historical and metaphysical' depends on 
precisely what these modifying adjectives imply, and whether they are 
meant to constitute an exhaustive classification. Wittgenstein offers us 
reason to doubt whether tcll^ious historical beliefs arc likL: other kinds 
of historical belief; and whilst we have no reason to expect metaphysi- 
cal beliefs to he any less liable to influence the religious thinking of 
human beings than their moral or scientific thinking, we have as 
yet no reason to think that they are ineliminahlc or dominant. This 
question, howcvciH raises issues that can be more fruitfully pursued by 
examining the uses to which Wiltgenslcinians have put Wittgenstein's 
own insights. 

Before we go on to that section of the paper, however^ I would like to 
conclude by pointing out that the fundamental observation from 
which the rest of Witlgcnstein^s claims derive - the idea that religious 
beliefs arc very different from empirical bchefs - is itself hardly original 
l-or it amounts Lo no more than a reiteration of the core argument In 
Part I of Kierkegaard's pseudonymous text Concluding Unscientific 
Postscript,*" which comprises chapters In which Climacus examines the 
.pbfectivc question posed by Christianity' and concludes tfiat religious 
beliefs cannot be a species of historical belief because 'the greatest 
attainable certainhr' with respect to anything historical is a mere 
approximaUon'. Of course^ Wittgenstein restates this claim In his own 
terms, and thereby eliminates from it Climacus's dubious assumption 
that tliere can be no such thing as certainty with respect to historical 
beliefs; but the core of his idea remains untouched, and other themes 
from the Postscript (passion, indlreci communication^ despair] pervade 
the long paragraph from which Wittgenstein's remark about religious 
belief as a commitment to a system of reference Is taken. 

It strikes me thai a religious belief could only be something like a 
passionate commitment to a system of reference. Hence, although it's 
belief^ ifs really a way of livings or a way of assessing life. It's passion- 
ately seizing hold of tl:ils inlcrprelatiDn. Instruction in a religious faith, 
therefore, would have to take the form of a portrayal, a description, of 
tliat system of reference^ while at the same time being an appeal to 
conscience- And this combination would have to result in the pupil 
himself, of his own accord, passionately taking hold of the system of 



Stephen Miiih^tf 103 

reference. It would be a5 though someone were first to let me see the 
hopelessness of my stluatLon and then show me the means of rescue 
until, of niy own accord, or not at any rate led to it by my instructor, I 
ran to it and grasped it lC\ p. 64). 

But of course, these themes wfll have been familiar to theologians 
and philosophers of religion for a number of years - they constitute a 
Ion S" re cognized mode of understanding Christianity and its relation 
to moraliLy and philosophy, one which is certainly not universally 
accepted but which is equally certainly taken to be a substantial and 
respectable theological option, and which long pre-dates any influence 
Wittgenstein's v^rilings and teaching have exerted. Why, then, when 
WittgcnsEein restates these familiar themeSn should they have elicited 
such an apparently undismissable intensity of interest and hostility 
from philosophers of religion? Perhaps an examiiiation of the work of 
those influenced by Wittgenstein's remarks will help to account for 
this ollierwise puzzling phenomenon. 



Wittgensteinian interprutations of religion 

Ever since the publication of Kai Neilscn's article eiitiltcd 'Wittgenstein- 
ian fideistn'/ certain fundamental misunderstandings about the nature 
of Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion have embedded themselves 
seemingly beyond recovery in the collective philosophical unconscious. 
Writers influenced by Wittgenstein - particularly D.Z. Phillips - have 
identified and attempted to rebut these misconceptions so oflei^ and so 
forcefully that it would seem entirely otiose c^'cn to raise the qucstiori 
again, if it were not for the fact that these rebuttals have been so singu- 
larly unsuccessful in achieving their aim of clarif^^ing the true implica- 
tions of the Wittgensteinian approach. What 1 want to do, then, is look 
at this issue one more time - not so much with the aim of tr^-'ing to 
settle the dispute^ but in order to try to understand a little more clearly 
why we seemed doomed endlessly to repeat the dance of mutual mis- 
understanding that this dispute now seems destined to embody. 

What makes the incradicabtlity of the term 'Wittgensteinian Fideism' 
so puzzling is that its users manage thereby to imply two radically con- 
tradictory linos of criticism simultaneously The first is that Wittgen- 
steinian approaches illegitimately lender traditional rcligioti immune 
to criticism; the second is that they illegitimately crilicizc traditional 
religious attempts to justify faith- Niclsen^s original article focuses on 



104 Fffihiwptiy of fif/i^ii^n p;i the 21 it Century 

the former line of arguracntj claimmg that according to certain followers 
of WiUgcnstcin: 

pUiiigion] can only be understood of criticised, and then onty In a 
piecemeal waVr from within this mode by someone who has a par- 
ticipant's understanding of lliis mode of discourse. To argue..- thai 
the very first-order discourse of this form of life is incoherent or 

irrational can be nothing but a confusion, for it is this very form 
of life, this very form of discourse itself, that sets its own criteria of 
coherence, intelligihility or rationality. PhLJosopiiy cannot rcle- 
vantly criticise relt^ion; it can only display for us the workings, the 
style of functioning, of religious discourse. (WP, p. I9'i) 

Hyman's article includes a trenchant version of the latter line of 
argument. 

[S]incc evidence and argument are not the exclusive property of 
science, Witlgcnstein cannot be right to insist that if we try to prove 
or support the proposition lliat God exists^ we are treating religion 
as if it were science, and are therefore already trapped in confusion. 
It would, 1 thinks be a mistake to maintain tliat because Anselm and 
Aquinas sought to prove the existence of God, tliey were peddling a 
variety of pseudo-science, a superstition which has notliing to do 
with reli^ous faith. (IWM, p. 261) 

It is certainly difficult to sec how anyone could maintain both lines 
of argument simultaneously^ but might not one or the other of them 
ne\^ertheless be sound? 

It must be admitted at once that the ways in whicli some Wittgen= 
stcinians liavc expressed themselves has helped to give some founda- 
tion to the first of these lines of criticism. For example, Hyman is 
rightly critical of D.Z. Phillips^s recently expressed, incautious bul 
revealing claim that: 



If the notton of an inner substance caHcd 'tlie soul' is the philo- 
sophical chimera we have suggested it is, whatever is meant by the 
immortahiy of the soul cannot be the continued existence of such a 
substance. (DS-^ p. 2371 

Since, as Hyman says, there is no obvious reason why it should be 
impossible to espouse, sincerely and seriously, demonstrably incoherent 



Stephen S4iiih^tf HJ5 



doctrines^ Pliillips's inference is plainly invalid; and the fact that he 
failed Lo notice this plausibly suggests Ihat he has a Lcndcncy to assume 
that religious beliefs and forms of life are essentially not illusory (if not 
necessarily beyond criticism), i^evcrlhelcss^ such remarks can and should 
be dismissed as incidental sEips unless it can t>e demonstrated that a 
similar tendency infects principles that arc at the heart of the VViUgcn- 
steinian approacli to the philosophy of rcli^Jion; and we have good 
reason for thinking that they arc not. 

For example, D.Z. Phillips has repeatedly argued that Nielsen^s worries 
are entirely unfounded^ because they fail to acknowledge that Witlgcii- 
steinian analyses of religious belief work not by isolating religious 
discourse and practice from the rest of human experience and life but 
by relating them to it. The process of clarifying tlie meaning of a reli- 
gious concept certainly involves relating that concept to other retigious 
concepts^ and to the attitudes and beliefs that go to inakc up a religious 
way of life; but it also Involves relating that system of concepts^ atti- 
tudes and beliefs to more general human phenomena. Praying to God^ 
for example, makes sense only because human life includes experiences 
and events for which God might intefligtbty be thanked, desires and 
purposes about which petitions might be made^ and actioi:is and 
thoughts which nnight intelligibly form the subject of a confession or 
request for absolution. It is precisely because religious faith can be pre- 
sented as one way of responding to the ordinary problems, perplexities 
and joys which most people experience at some point in their lives 
that it has the importance it does have for so many people. 

[nsofar as it presents a religious system of reference in its natural 
setting like thls^ a Wlttgensteinian account not only gives itself the 
resources to make religious concepts intelligible to non-believers as well 
as believers; it is also able to show that both groups have access to a 
number of perfectly legiLlmaie ways of criticizing or rejecting modes 
of life that employ religious concepts. To begin with, religious systems 
of reference contain their own distinctive terms of criticism. Even 
setting aside the ways In which l>cllevcrs might discriminate orthodoxy 
from heresy or blasphemy, there is also the category of superstition; it 
is perfectly common for believers to criticize fcllow-believcrs on the 
grounds that their claims and actions manifest what one might call a 
magical or sentimental conception of the deity, and it is perfectly pos- 
sible for those outside the relevant religious tradition to comprehend 
and endorse such criticisms, Phillips^ for example, makes much of 
Wlttgenstcin^s criticisms of the scapegoat rite as described in Leviticus, 
in the course of which he argues that the use of an animal to shoulder 



106 Fffihiwphy of fif/igii^n p;i the 21 it Century 



the peoplc^s burden of sinfulness can plausibly be rejected as einbodying 
a confused and crude understanding of how freedom from sin might be 
achieved. 

Hcwcvcrj Phillips also famously makes rather more external criticisms 
of certain mainsta)^ of traditional theoEogical and religious thinking in 
Christianily^ I am thinking here of hi.s critique of traditional solutions 
to the problem of evil^ or of the standard proofs of God^s existence. 
Plainly, such criticisms presuppose a certain grasp of the nature and 
signihcance of the religious tradition from which tlie lx:liefs and prac- 
tices under criticism have emerged - how else can vvc ensure thai those 
ertticisms are accurately aimed? But they do not use terms of criticism 
tliat are generated or deployed exclusively by believers - importaaitly 
because they depend upon invoking certain connections between 
religious attitudes and the more general phenomena of human life. 
Phillips^s critique of solutions to the problem of evil^ for example, 
depends primarlty upon certain central moral principles concerning the 
intrinsic and incommensurable value of human life^ and upon certain 
ordinary human responses to the suffering of others - principles and 
responses that are plainly not the cxiuslvc preserve of those within a 
religious tradition. 

Moreover, although Phillips does not make mucli of this possibility 
in his writings^ there is no reason w^hy even more apparently externa] 
modes of criticism might not be deployed against religious belief in 
a manner consistent with Wittgenstein^s principles- For example^ 
Nietzsche's suspicions of Christianity as embodying sado-masochistic 
5elf-hatrcd^ and Trcud's suspicions of institutionalized religion as pan- 
dering to psychologically Immature dependence on a father-figure 
should both provide food for thought even tor believers. They identify 
new forms - or at leasl potentially illuminate nc\v interpretations of 
old forms - of religious pathology, and help to alert a believer to per- 
Jbaps unappreciated variants of the ills to which religious thought and 
practice is heir 

Wlttgenstelnlans would, however^ be less comfortable with the idea 
tliat such theories might legitimately be used to justify a wholesale 
rejection of religious belief as such - exactly the i^ind of rejection 
which Ncilsen^ for example, wishes to leave open. Here again, unfortu- 
nately, this discomfort has been formulated - by Witlgenstcinians and 
perhaps by Wittgenstein hiniselt - in potcniially misleading ways. 
Phillips, for example, quotes the following remark of Wittgenstein's as 
support for his claim that^ whilst we can legitimately criticize certain 
religious rituals as confused or superstitious^ we cannot make the same 



Stephen S4iiihM IQ7 

criticisin of religious practices as a whole. It is true that we can compare 

a picture that is firmly rooted [n us to a superstition; but it i^ equally 
true that we always eventually have to reach some firm ground, either 
a picture or something clsc^ so that a picliirc ivhich is at the foot of 
all our thinking Is to be respected and not treated as a superstition 
(CV, p. &3K 

The context of this remark makes it unclear exactly what Wittgenstein 
has ill mind when he talks of 'a plctuic at the root of all our thinking'^ 
but It is surely plain that the inference he proposes is invalid if we 
think of it in application to religious pictures. For ftom the fact that 
certain religious pictures guide an individual's hfe, and lie at the root of 
all that she says and docs, IL certainly docs not follow thai they are 
worthy of respect- Why, after all, should the depth or jx^rvasive influ- 
ence of a picture make it incoherent to judge that it embodies a 
degrading or innmature attitude to life? What is needed for me to make 
such a criticism is^ as Wittgenstein says, some firm ground from Avhich 
to evaluate the rehpious picture, a competing picture or something 
else of tlic kind that is fundamental to my life; but such pictures are 
precisely designed to proi-ide a base from which to criticize opposing 
pictures that lie at the root of other people's lives. Indeed, one of the 
key facts about rclij^ous pictures nowadays is that, although they lie at 
tlie root oi some people's thinking, they do not lie at the root of our 
thinking, of e\'eryone's thinking: hence, unhke the pictures to which 
Wittgenstein appears to be referring^ they arc precisely open to criti- 
cism and lejection. 

There arc^ however, other and bcLter reasons for baulking at the 
thought of a wholesale re}cction of religious belief as such; for such a 
rejection would fail to acknowledge even the possibility that certain 
versions of such ways of life might avoid the ills to which others 
succumb- It Is far from easy to see how there could be an a priori 
demonstration that aU possible ways of deploying religious systems of 
reference are pathological^ because tliat would amount to establisiiLng 
that it is impossible even to conceive of a way of using those concepts 
as part of a form of life that does not manifest the relevant attitudes 
(of sado-masochism or immaturity). 

These qualms become even more overwhelming when the critic 
wishes - as does KaL NeLlsen - to he able to reject a religious mode of 
discourse as a whole on the grounds that Lt is incoherent or irrational or 
llloKtcaL There is^ of course, no difficulty with the idea that someone 
might regard religious belief as imprudent ^like gambling) or oppressive 
(like footbinding) or pointless (like motor racing}; and given that the 



ins Flrihiwphy ofRi^Hsfou m the 21 it Century 

laws of logic apply to religious discourse as they do to any others a 
religious statement that is on the face of ti logically iticohcrcm (such as 
■"God Is three and one') stands in need of an exptanalion which reveals 
that this is not in fact so. But there can be no ground foi assuming a 
priori that such an explanation cannot he forthcoming; we have to look 
and sec how the statement ftinctions in the relevant context before we 
can establish what it means. And shice any attempt to demonstrate the 
global irrationality of religious belief as such must presuppose that the 
rettgious discourse under criticism has a particular si^nfficancEp it will 
fail to apply to any actual or possible inode of employing that discourse 
which confers a different significance upon it. 

What, then, of the opposing weakness attributed to 'Wittgcnstclnlan 
Fldclsts' - their tendency not to render religious belief Immune from 
radical criticism, but rather to subject traditional modes of defending 
religious belief to radical criticism? Note that the real issue here is not 
whether or not Wittgensteinlan accounts can consistently contlict with 
what religious believers are inclined at first blush to say about theiE 
beliefs aiid practices. As Phillips has repeatedly pointed out: 

[Tlhe suggestion [that we should accept the believer's gloss as the 
last word on the issuel is baffling. These philosophers would not 
dream of advocating this procedure elsewhere In philosophy. 1 can 
be told any day of the WTck In my local pub that thlitking is a state 
of consciousness. Does tiiat settle the matter? (^WRj'"" p. 243) 

A Wittgensteinlan ts coniniittedj not to the defence of common sense, 
but to the clarification of the grammar of the words In whicli common 
sense and any other inteliiglbie utterances are given expression. What 
provides that clarirication In the case of leligious belief is not whatever 
religious believers are at first inclined to say about themselves - that is 
philosophical raw material, not its end-product - but rather how they In 
fact employ religious concepts in the practices which go to make up 
their lives- Any Interesting version of this line of criticism must therefore 
make out a ease for the claim that WlttgensLeinian approaches arc com= 
mitted to subjecting traditional religious practices to radical criticism. 

Myman's way of developing this claitii unfortunately begins from a 
mistaken reading of Wittgenstein's claims about this issue. His argu- 
mcnt, as we saw earlier, ruiis as follows: 



[Sjince evidence and argument are not the exclusive property of 
science^ Wittgenstein cannot be right to insist that if we try to prove 



Stephen S4iiih^{f IQ9 

or support the proposition that God exists, wc arc treating rcHgion 
as if it wcFC science, and arc therefore already trapped in confusion. 
It would, 1 think, be a mistake to maintain that because Ansclm and 
Aquinas sought to prove the existence of God, tlicy were peddling a 
variety of pseudo-seicncc, a superstition which has nothing to do 
Willi religious l^aith. (IWXJ^ p. 261) 



Til cffeci, Hynian assumes that, because Wittgenstein in his lectures 
accuses one Fatlier O'Hara of illicitly transforming religious belief into 
supH^rstitionj then he is comnilued to accusing Ansclni and Aquinas of 
the same error. But what Wittj^enstein actually objects to in O'Hara's 
approach is that he is 'one of those people who make [religious belief] 
a question of science' [LQ p. 57); in other words, he treats a belief in 
God's existence as a kind of empirical hypothesis, and so treats God as 
a kind of physical object oi entity. So the criticism w^ould only transfer 
to Anselm or Aquinas if their attempts to defend or support religious 
belief betrayed a simitar tendency. Hyman thinks that they do because 
he thinks that Willgenstein regards any attempt to support religious 
belief as tantamount to treating religion as if it were science, liut this 
is sinipty not true: Wittgenstein thinks that it would be as misleading 
to present religious belief as reasonable as it would be to describe it as 
irrational^ but he docs not ililnk Lhat there is no such thing as arguing 
about or offering reasons for or against religious belief. On the contrary, 
he tells us that ^[religious] controverstes look quite different from any 
normal controversies- Reasons look entirely different from normal rca- 
scns^ (LQ p. 56) - remarks which presuppose that there are such things 
as religious contTovcrsies^ and reasons for and against religious bclicL 

Wliether or not Anselm and Aquinas fall foul of Wittgenstein's criti- 
cism therefore depends, not on whether or not they try to defend their 
religious beliefs^ but on how they do so - on whether or not they 
involve treating God as a kind of physical objeetn or treating a belief in 
God's existence as a kind of empirical h)^olliesis. The simple fact that 
tliese proofs tend to mlntmlze as far as possible any reliance upon 
empirical premiseSn and aspire to establishing certainty of a kind more 
akin to that available in the realms of mathematics and logic than that 
of science, suggests that there might at least be initial grounds for dis- 
tinguishing Father O'Hara's efforts from tliosc of his illustrious prede- 
cessors- And of course, Wittgenstcinian philosophers pf religion have 
devoted much labour to the task of showing that, although traditional 
proofs of God's existence of tlie kind offered by Anselm and Aquinas 
can be understood as versions of Father O'Hara 's kind of thinking, they 



no Flrihiwphy ofRi^iisiou m the 21 it Century 



need not be. Phillips'^ analyses of the ar;^nicn1: from Design and the 
Cosmologieal argument are one example of this nuanced Ireatment; 
but Norman Malcohrt^s account of Ansclni^s Iwo versions of the Onto- 
logical aigumciil is perhaps the single most influential and impressive 
example of this kind of Wiftgensteinian work, since it aims to establish 
Ihat the whole point of the Ontological argument Is to remind us that 
God is not ^eine Existenz\ NevcrthelesSj insofar a^ Anselm and Aquinas 
or their followers have understood their proofs to be proofs of an 
empirical hypothesis, and lo have embodied such an understanding in 
(heir practices, then they will indeed count as supcrstUious from a 
Wittgensteinian j>crspective. And the critics take it that such a categoriza- 
tton of certain religious practices and perspectives amounts to a species 
of prescriptive revisionism, and so as antithetical to Wittgenstein i an 
descriptive methods - as subverting their claim to be merely describing 
the practices and forms of ilfe with language that are the focus of iheir 
philosophical concern. Phillips has attempted to block this inference 
by denying that such categorizations have an^ critical or rc\asionary 
implications: ''Whether a ritual is superstitious is shown in its practice. 
Philosophy, in making this explicit, is not prescriptive' (WR^ p. 245). 

Thi.^ claim lacks any real plausibility, however for of course, ^ven If 
the applicability of the concept of 'superstition^ to a given practice can 
l>e judged only by descril?ing tiie form of that practice, the concept 
Itself has a primarily critical force, and criticism implies the need for 
change: superstition is, after all^ something to be avoided- So^ if Phillips 
succeeded in demonstrating to the satisfaction of a given religious 
believer that some aspect of their beliefs, rituals or practices deserved 
to be called ^superstitious^ he would have s^ven them the best possible 
reason to alter it in the direction of a more genuinely religious attitude 
to life. Such believers mifjht well be grateful for the intervention. After 
all, since all religious traditions alter over time (In part because of shifts 
in the theological and philosophical understandings of their concepts 
aiid practices)^ their adherents might actually come to embrace rcvi- 
slonary accounts of their traditional self-understandings as embodying 
a deeper understanding of the true nature of their inheritance- Any 
such intervention would, however, undeniably be revisionary in its 
consequences. 

The charge of ' prescript! vism' cannot, therefore, be as easily dis- 
missed as Phillips seems to think. Biit it is important to acknovslcdge 
that Wittgensteinians are not here engaging in the business of using 
one language game to combat another, deploying mcKies of criticism 
that are entirely external or alien to the practices criticized - fox the 



Stephen S4iiiimt} 111 

t€rms of criticism deployed arc ones which form a more or less intimate 
part of the system of reference under descFiptlon. To put tt in PhtMips's 
preferred terminology: certain confusions in certain religious practices 
are identified by reference to other aspects of what religious believers 
say and do, both as part of their explicitly religious lives and as part 
of their common moral and intellectual Inheritaiice. NeverthelesSn this 
identification of confusion cannot be uncoupled from its critical or 
prescriptive implications; and ihis does suggest that Wittgenstelnians 
must reconcile themselves to acknowledging that there is at lea^t one 
important sense iti whicli their philosophical practice does not 'leave 
everj^thing as it is' - that it does not accept forms of life as given. And 
since the terms of criticism employed (ones which identify confusions 
as species of 'superstition^ and so on) have their original home in reli- 
gious or spiritual contexts, the question arises: is there a more than 
purely coincidental relation betw^een a Wittgensteinian philosophical 
practice and religious forms of life? Why is It that a prescrlpUve 
element tn Wittgensteinian philosophy seems to emerge most expHc- 
itly and naturally with respect to religion? 



Religious iuttipfitaflaons of Wittgenstein 

Wittgenstein himself famously remarked: ''I am nol a religious man^ 
but 1 cannot help seeing every problem from a religious point of view' 
(RW, p. 79). 

This remark can only confirm the feelings of those who - in w^hat 
appear to be increasing numbers in recent years - claim to detect an air 
of spiritual fervour throughout Wtttgensietn's philosophical writings^ 
both early and late- It has recently been the focus of a wonderfully illu- 
iiiinaling discussion between two of the most hi^^hly respected mem- 
bers of a group of philosophers whose work was heavily influenced 
by Wittgenstein's own thought- Normaii Malcolm and Peter Winch;'^^ 
and I would like to conclude this essay tay exploring that exchange. 
Even though its full elaboration was cut short by his untimely death, 
Malcohn's view of the matter is fairly clearly summarized at the end of 
his essay. 



[T|here are four analogies betw^ecn Witlgenstein^s conception of the 
grammar of language, and his \^ew of what is paramount in a religious 
life. First, in both there is an end to explanation; second, in toth 
there is an inclination to be amazed at the existence of something 



112 Fmitiwphy ofRi^n^ou m the 21 it Century 

[language gameSj in the one casc^ and the world, in the other]; thirdj 
into both there enters the notion of an ""illness'; fourth, in lioth, doiaigj 
acting, takes prLor[t>^ over Lntcllectijal understanding and reasoning- 
(Rf^: p. 92) 



I thinlc it is fair to say thai Peter Winch's tactful but relentless essay in 
response to Malcolm's own shows beyond doubt that both ihe main 
elements and ihe overall approach ol Malcolm's analysis ate seriously 
awry, hi particular, the claimed analogies can appear to hold only if 
one Fails to acknowledge not only critical differences between the sig- 
nificance of similar words employed in very different contexts, but also 
what Wittgenstein would think of as critical differences between philo- 
sophical and religious approaches to phenomena tn general. Thus^ for 
example. Winch points out thai the first of Malcolm's four analogies 
runs together two distinct points of comparison - that the expression 
of religious belief is itself a language-game for which it makes no sense 
to ask for an explanation, and that for the religious belie^^er within 
such a language game a reference to God^s will signals ^an end to expla- 
nation'- But the former point holds of all language games, and so falls 
to distinguish religious practices from ^ny otheip whereas the latter 
precisely marks a disanalogy beUvecn philosophy and religion, since 
no VVlttgensteinlan Is, as it were, professionally committed to the view 
that we must accept lan^age games as they are because their existence 
and specific form are manifestations of God^s wilL On a more general 
level, Winch is suspicious of the particular angle from which Malcolm 
approaches the remark Wittgenstein Is reported to have made, and 
which his four analogies are designed to elucidate. For^ quite apart 
fiom the fact that our only evidence for its having been made is the 
recollection of a friend, Winch is alert to the further fact that, as 
reported^ Wittgenstein's remark identifies the religious point of \1ew as 
that from which he approaches 'every problem' - not every philosoph- 
ical problemj as Malcolm presupposes. At best^ therefore^ It can be held 
to characterize Wittgenstein's relation to philosophical problems, and 
so his philosophical practice, only insofai as it characterizes his rela- 
tion to the problems of life as a whole - and not, as Malcolm assumes, 
entirely Independently of that general attitude. Nevertheless, Winch is 
inclined to see that something important about Wittgenstein's philo- 
sophical practice is captured by the reported remark^ and he ends his 
response to Matcolm by sketching in his own interpretation of it. This 
sketch is more than a little difficult to render consistent in places_ For 
example^ after makinj^ a connection between Wittgenstein's views of 



Stephen S4iiih^{f 113 

religtoii and of philosophy by talking of the passion A-vith which he 
practises the latter^ and iioUng that VVtttgcnslcin follows Kierkegaard in 
contrasting Ihe passion of faith with the cold passionlessness of 
wisdom, Winch immediately suggests ihaL the l*hi!osophLcal hivcstiga- 
tlons can tae Ihought of as expressing Wittgenstein's ideal of 'a certain 
coohicss_ A temple providing a setting for the passions without 
meddling with them^ (CV^ p. 1). In the end, however^ the key point 
Winch wishes to make emerges quite clearly: it Involves a sense that "for 
someone to whom philosophical issues matter^ a lack of clarity ahout 
them can have grave implications for his or her own rclalion to life' 

fRPV, p. uai ■ ^ ■ - 

Winch illustrates his point by referring to a passajjc by Wittgenstein 
on how the sensation of pain can have a relation to a human body. 

Blit isn't it absurd to say of a body that it has pain? - And why does 
one feel an absurdity in that? In w-hat sense is It true that my hand 
docs not feel pain, but 1 In my hand? 

What sort of issue is: Is it the body that feels pain? - How is it to 
be decided? What makes it plausible to say that it is not the body? - 
Well, something like this: If somcoiic has a pain in his hand^ then 
the hand docs not say so (unless it writes it) and one does not com- 
fort the hand, but the sufferer: one looks into his face. (PI/' ^ p. 2K6) 

Winch's commentary on this passage deserves quotation in full. 

That last sentence gives me a wonderful sense of a fog suddenly 
hfting; the eonfused shapes that loom up and disappear again in the 
familiar philosophical discussions of 'mind and body' vanish and 1 
am left with a clear view of something very familiar of which 1 had 
not noticed the importance- Its importance' lies in the first instance 
in its relation to the philosophical discussion. At the same time in 
attending to the minute detail that plays such an enormous role in 
our relations to each other, my sense of the dimensions of those 
relations is boQi transformed and enriched: when comforting some- 
one who has been hurl, I look into the sufferer's eyes, (RPV, p. 130) 



i find this passage to be just as wonderful as the passage from Wittgen- 
stein to which it is a response; but it sec ins to me that two qualifications 
Winch imposes on the scope of its implications are difficult to justifj^ 

First, we might ask: is it really plausible to restrict the transformation 
and enrichment that Wittgenstcm's grammatical reminders can engender 



1 14 FIriio.wphy ofRi^fi^ou Ui the 21 it Century 



lo 'our sense of the dimensions of our interpersonal relations? Winch 
figures WUigcnstciii'"s insights as removing the fog wliich has blocked 
my view of something entirely familtarp he thereby restricts the trans- 
formation those insights produce to our understanding of our lives 
rather than to what is thereby understood. The idea is that philosophi- 
cal confusions reside exclusively in tlie views we take of our lives, not 
the lives themselves. But this seems a particularly artificial distinction 
With respect to grammatical reminders about psychological concepts. 
Take, for cxaniiple^ Wittgenstein's related reminders concerning the 
commonly expressed philosophical view that no other person can have 
exactly the same pain as me; Wittgenstein argues that this view depends 
upon incoherently treating the possessor of the pain as a property of it, 
and so manifests a false sense of our scparateness as persons by imposing 
a non-existent uniqueness on our experience. Bui the scepticism of 
which this liclief is the intellectual expression is also something that 
can and does pervade our ordinary liveSn affecting not just our sense of 
the dimensions of interpersonal relations but the dimensions them- 
selves. We can and do exist within this mislocaled sense of our sepa- 
ratencss and commonality; we live our scepticism. 

Winches second qualification finds expression in his claim thai the 
spiritual implications of grammatical unclarity apply only to those for 
whom philosophical issues matter. This restriction is reinforced and 
explained in a footnote, which reads: '1 make this qualification since 
1 am sure that Wittgenstein did not - like Socrates? - want to make 
philosophical clarity quite generally a sine qua non of spiritual health' 
(Rpy p- 135). If lA^e question Wtcich's first qualification hy questioning 
the distinction hetwecn oiLr philosophically expressed views of life and 
our lives themselves, tliis second qualification will already look rather 
implausible. But there are also independent grounds for concern; for 
tl;ie second qualification seems to depend upon an equally artificial 
distinction between those for whom philosophical Issues matter and 
those for whom they do not. Firsts if Winches own line of argument 
is correct, there can tae no-one who stands in need of philosophical 
clarity for whom that clarity cannot matter; if yoti suffer from the 
confus^on^ you need the clarity - that clarity matters to you - w^hethcr 
you know it or not. So tlie distinction which his qualification really 
presupposes must be one between those for whom philosophical prob- 
lems arisc^ and those for whom they do not. But any such distinction 
can be at best provisional, for there is no jjood reason to think that 
there arc any human beings who are constitutionally immune to philo- 
sophical confusions^ any creature complicated enough Co be burdened 



Stephen S4iiih^t} 115 

by language is necessarily vulnerable to such confusions. To be surc^ a 
given person at a given time might escape contusion^ and so stand in 
no need of graininaticaL clarity at that time- after all, one migtit almost 
define a philosophical prohlem as one Vn^liieh is not always live for us, 
but whichn once living, is undism is sable. But this temporary freedom 
has nothing to do with whether or not one is a professional phUoso- 
phcr^ or wcU-cducatcdj or an inhabitant of complex civilizations - as 
Winch's qualification seems to nnply. The truth of the matter is that 
philosophical confusions are not restricted to inhabitants of certain 
disciplines^ or sectors of culture, or classes within societies^ or societies 
as a whole. They are part of our inheritance as human beings; and In 
this important sense, philosophical issues matter to everyone. If^ then^ 
we contemplate pushing beyond Winch's conclusions by removing his 
two restrictions, but in the direction that those conclusions have 
already sketched out^ we might feel the need to inquire a little more 
closely Into the nature of the philosophical confusions agalnsL which 
Wittgenstein sets the resources of his philosophical practice of remind- 
ing us of what we say when, recalling us to the grammar or criteria of our 
ordinary words, if such recalling is necessary, that must be because 
our confusion has ted us to go beyond those criteria - to lose control of 
our words, to attempt to speak outside or beyond language games. But 
how and why might we make such an attempt? Why and how can oth- 
erwise competent speakers suffer such a loss of control when under the 
pressure to philosophize? 

We know that, for Wittgenstein, that over whicli they lose control - 
criteria - constitute the iimits or conditiojis of the human capacity to 
knoWn think or speak about tlic world and the various things that are in 
it: they are that without which human knowledge of the world would 
not be possible. But of course, it is fatally easy to interpret limits as Eimi- 
tationSn to experience conditions as constraints. Indeed, this is precisely 
how the sceptic often understands her owtl motives^ she repudiates our 
ordinary reliance upon criteria because she regards what we ordinarily 
count as knowledge as itothing of the kind, as failing to put us Into 
contact with the world as it really is. Liut it would only make sense to 
think of the conditions of liuman kaiowlcdgc as limitatioi:fcs if we could 
conceive of another cognitive perspective upon the world that did 
not require them; and philosophers from Kant onwards liave variously 
striven to show diat there is no such perspective - tliat tlie absqice of the 
concepts or categories in terms of which we individuate olisfccts would 
not clear the way for unmediated knowledge of the world, but would 
rather remove the possibility cf anything that might count as knowledge. 



11 "6 Flfiio.wptiy ofRi'fi^o^f p;i the 21 it Century 



]n other words^ what the sceptic understands as a process of dsstllu- 

sionmciiL In the name of true knoivlcdgc, Wittgcnslclii inlctprcls as an 
inability or refusal to acknowledge tlic fact that liuinan knowledge - 
Uie knowledge available to flnilc creatures, subjective agents m an 
objective world - is necessarily conditioned. But it Is worth rccaHlng 
lliat nothing is more human than llie desire lo deny the human, to 
interpret limits as limitations and to repudiate (he human condition 
of conditioncdness or finitude in the name of (he unconditioned, 
the transcendent, the superhuman - the inhuman. On this under- 
standing of criteriaj the human desire to speak outside language 
games is an inflection of the pridcful human craving to be God, and 
Witlgenste ill's philosophical practice aims not so much to eradicate 
this ineradicable hubris but to diagnose it and track dowMi the causes 
of its specific eruptions from case to case of its ^ercmilal^ endlessly 
renewed realization. 

An interpretation of Wittgenstein's method along these lities has 
been most famously advanced and elaborated by Stanley Cayell, who 
thinks of philosophy practised under such a self-understanding as a 
species of perfectionism.^^ in Cavell's thought, the unending sequence 
of specific manifestations of scepticism in modcrnily reveals that 
human beings are possessed of a nature in which the sceptical impulse 
is {apparently) ineradicably Inscribed- Whal is needed ifit is to be com- 
bated is a fully acknowledged relationship with a particular human 
other fthc philosopher, whether Wittgenstein or tliose who would 
inherit his task) - one whose words have the power to identif^^ and 
make us ashamed of our present confused and disoriented slatc^ one 
ivhOj by excmplifving a further^ attainable state of clarity and self- 
possession^ can attract us to it whils( respecting our autonomy and 
iridi\'iduality. Now, measure this self-understanding against the follow- 
ing theological structure- In Christian thought, our unending sequence 
of particular sinful acts reveals that human beings are possessed of a 
nature which disposes Lheni to sin and prevents them from escaping 
(lielr bondage tay using their own rx^sources. \Miat they need to attain 
Llieii new nature is a fully acknowledged relationship with a particular 
person - one through whose words divine grace is made accessibte, one 
who exemplifies the further, unattained but attainable human state to 
which God wishes to attract every individual whilst respecting her 
freedom to deny its attractions and spurn His grace. Against this 
background^ it is not just a sense of Hic reality of our hubristic railings 
against our finilude that links Wittgenstein Ian philosophy and religion. 



Stephen Miiih^tf 117 

but a surprisingly detailed conception of its precise forms and of the 

available ways of attcmpUng lo overcome Ihem. Tlic precision of the 
mapping here might well be what underlay the third of llic analogies 
Malcolm wi5hcd to draw between Witt^cnstein^s view of pliilosophical 
problems and religious belief, and to which Winch devotes compara- 
tli'cly liLtlc attention in his response: that bctvi;ccn ihe religious atti- 
tude of regarding oneself as radically imperfect or 'sick' and the idea 
that philosophical puzzlement is a sympiora of a disease. It may be, 
in other words, that some recognizable inflection of the notion of 
Original Sin is more pertinent to the insight thai Winch himself 
began lo develop than he was able to see, that he and Malcolm were in 
this sense less far apart than may appear. Whatever the truth of this 
matter, it seems at least arguable that if we arc to attain a deeper under- 
standing of Wittgenstein's 'religious point of view', and attain thereby 
a better grasp of the uncanny, undismissablc intimacy between 
Wittgenstelnlan philosophy of religion and jc]]gioii itself^ we would 
do well to take seriously Stanley CavelTs interpretation of the 
Philosophical hivcstigations. 



Notes 



L in LiTiiirf.T wui Cvfivef':^^liofis Gfi At^sth^tics^ Psy^chofo^' 4Ufd Rch^ima Bi'Uef, edited 
by Cyril Barrett (Lrniveisitj- o( Calikjmia Press, Berkeley, 1966) - ]iijrt:after LC, 

2- Edited by G.U. von Wright and H- Nyman, trans, Peter Winch {Oxford: 
Easi] B3ackwell, 19801 - hereafter CV. 

3- Edited by Rush Rhte& (OKford Uiicversity Press, Oxford, 19J51 1 - hereafter RW. 

4. Edited by Quinn aniJTaEiafeiro I Oxford: Elackwell, 3997>-pp. I5fJ-S. 

5. In^ead of referring to lii& Companion entry, I ^hall use quotations from 
Dt Hyman's earlier paper 'Immortality without Metaphysics' (pubiii^hed 
in DZ_ Phj[lip5 (edj. Can R^'li,^hm Be E-xplitifud Away? (LDndoni St Martin'5 
Press, 1996[ - hereaftei IWM), where he advances exactly the same lines of 
argument- Since the original paper was presented at an earlier Claremont 
Conference, this choice of reference point seem-ed best suited to the present 
occasion, 

6. Trans- H-V. an J ELH. Hong {Piincelon, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1992 J - 
hereafter CUR 

7. Philosophy XLII, No- 1^51,July 1967 - hereafter Wl-- 

S. ^Dislocating the Souf , the es-say to which Hyman's own article 'Immortaliry 
without Metapliyi^ics"' is a leply^ is published in the same coiiection. 

9. D.Z- PhilhpSj. Witt,^e?rsteiii luid Reii^lmi (London: MacmiHan, 19931 - here^ 

after WR. 
10- N. Malcolm, Wini{en^tehi: ti Reii^iima Poiul of View? (editcid vvkh a response 
by Peter Winch) (London: RoutEedge, 19?3j - hereafter RPV- 



US Flriitiwphy ofRi^Hsfou m the 21 it Century 



11. L Wittgenstein (trans. C^_E_M. Anscombe^j Pfilio:!iuptiical hivestigations 
COxfoid: ElackweSl, 1953)- 

12- Many of the key CaveJI texts are collected in 5. Mulhall (ed.;^ The diveit 
R^aJer {Oxford: Blackwell^ 19961 - see especially Essay 1 6 and the Epilogue. 
Further elaboration and defence of Cavell's inteipretation of Wittgenstein 
can bL" found in my Staniey CiiwU: PbUosopby's Recounting ^fttie Oniinary 
tOxfofd: OKfofd University Press, 1994) - see especially ch_ IZ- 



8 

Wittgenstein and the Philosophy 
of Religion: a Reply to Stephen 
Mulhall 

Waiford Gea}y 



I waitL to begin by congta tula ting Stephen Miilhall on his beautifully 
written and solidly constructed paper. The title givcn^ 'Wittgenstein 
and the l-'liiiosophy of kchgion' allowed the posslbilUy of a wide 
approach to be taken to the subject, and Mulhall has taken full advan- 
tage of ihis space in his tripartite rciponse. The excellence of some sec- 
tions of his paper has rendered any further comment on them wholly 
superfluous. I have particularly in mind those parts in which Mulhalt is 
critical of other writers^ such as his penetratingly astute ar^mcnts 
againstjohn Hyman in both the first and second divisions or the paper. 
However^ no t^vo people would have approached this set topic in the 
same way^ and Lhere are some issues ivhich I would have liked to have 
seen given greater emphasis, especially the assessment of Wittgenstein's 
contribution to the philosophy of rcttgion. But I also think thatj in 
some ways^ Mulhall could have been more critical of Witt^cnstcni's 
own views on religion- 1 appreciate that these commenLs are, of course, 
essentiallv evaluative, and I found it difficult to discover much that is 
amiss with Mulhairs logic. In my reply I wish to concentrate primarily 
on the first part of MulhalFs paper which deals specifically with 
Wittgenstein^s own comments on religion, including liiose remarks 
contained in the celebrated three lectures on religious belief, although 
what I have to say about these has some bearing on issues raised in the 
other two sections of MulhalTs essay. 

If the general question were asked^ 'What has Wittgenstein contributed 
to the philcfiophy of religion?' it would not he inappropriate, even for 
tiiosc who have embraced his standpoint^ to answer in t^vo apparently 
contradictory ways. On the one hand, it could be maintained that he 
contributed next to nothing to the subject, while, on the other hand, it 
could be claimed^ with some considerable justification, that no one in 



119 



120 Flrihiwptiy of fif/jgroiu in the 21 it Century 



this century has contrihutcd more to the discipline. On the negative side, 
Mulhal! refers to the 'few scauert:d pebbles' of Wittgenstein's remarks on 

religious belief - and it is induhitably the case that Wittgenstein lATOte 
very little about rcU^^ion- And^ in my view, what he did Avrite^ or perhaps 
more accurately as a generalization, what he is reported to have saUl 
aboijl religious faith, appears to me to be largely unimpressive - partic- 
ularly Troni a religious perspective - and, in philosophical termSn it is 
certainly not representative of, or even comparable with, wliat is best 
in Wittgenstein. His comments on religion often appear idiosyncratic 
and banalj and, sonicUmes, plainly incorrect. On the positive side, and 
in sharp contrast to the 'pebbles' alluded to, Wittgenstein's work on 
Ihe philosophy of logic and language appear, in Mulhairs own phrase, 
like 'mountainous ranges', and for most Wittgcnsteinian thinkers it is 
Ihe implications of this logic that makes his indirect contribuUon to 
the philosophy of rehgion so invaluable. Let us then look briefly at 
these different ways of evaluating Wittgenstein's contribution to this 
field of philosophy beginning with the positive aspect - the claim 
that, arguably^ Wittgenstein's contribution to the philosophy of reli- 
gion in this centurj^ is unparalleled. 

Even though it is fashtonabtc to distLnguish betis^cen the various 
philosophies of Wittgenstein, there Is, throughout his thinking, one 
central unif)'1ng preoccupation, l-roin Lhe very first he was solely con- 
cerned with the issue of the intelligibility of symbolism or of language. 
Tliis concern with the nature of language or symbolism had developed 
from his initial interest in mathematics and from his subsequent read- 
ing of the works of Frege and kusscIL As such, Wittgenstein's thinking 
forms part of a mder philosophical movement that iTccamc ultimately 
responsible for placing logical considerations at the heart of piiilosoph- 
ical activity, and that for the greater part of the twentieth century 
What this concern wnih logic displaced was epistemology - a discipline 
which, in Wittgenstein's earlier work, was relegated to the realm of 
psychology, while in his later work^ epistemology is seen to be, as most 
other philosophical Issues, the product of conceptual confusion- The 
traditional general question, ""What is the nature of knowledge?' is both 
misleading and ambiguous. It presupposes that there is such a thing as 
tlie essence of knowledge- But Wittgenstein showed that what knowl- 
edge amounts to depends on the context in which thp claim to knowl- 
edge is made^ and on how things 1iang together' wiLliin that specific 
context. So that to know myself, for instance, or to know what pain a 
person is going through, or to know that Cardiff is the capital city of 



Wafforti GeaSy IZl 



Wales, or that the chemical formula of salt is NaCl, or to know Godn 
arc different forms of knowing. In tlie sense thai each claim is connected 
with different sets of concepts that go together - so tliat what can be 
said or asked about each form of knowledge differs in each case. Or^ 
expressed in a different way, if one were challenged to defend one's 
claim to knowledge in any of these instances, tlie reply would be 
different - to a greater or Eesser extent. Wittgenstein s exhortation that 
we should consider if all gaines have something in common is equally 
applicable to the concept of knowledge. And if we iook and sce^ we 
have to arrive at the same conclusion that we 'will not sec soniclhing 
that is common to all, but similarities, relationships and a whole series 
of them at that^ (P.L, para 6S). Henee^ traditional epistemological sys- 
tems are confused attempts to get at the essence of knowledge - an 
essence that simply does not exist. 

When Mulhall icfcrs to the 'radical subversion to which Wittgenstein 
aimed to subject the discipline of plijlosophy" I suppose he was refer- 
ringn at least in part^ to this hindamental reorientation of the discipline 
away from epislemolog)' and tow-ards logic. The impact of this change 
is immeasurable: it displaced the central philosophical tradition that 
had heen rooted, certainly m Europe^ for ccnturics_ In Britain, for 
instance^ since the dawn of modern philosophy^ the dominant phiTo* 
sophical creed has been that of empiricism. From the middle of the sev- 
enteenth century to the twentieth, almost without exception, leading 
liritish philosophers (llobbeSn Locke, Berkeley^ HumCf Benlhamn Milln 
Russell and Mooreli have been empificists. Now^ although Mulhall may^ 
sadly^ be perfectly correct in stating dial Wittgenstein^s work may no 
longer 'hmction as an essential reference point" in many Ticlds of 
philosophical endeavour' (p. l)p those who have espoused the changes 
initiated by Wittgenstein sti!! perceive these as constituting the 
strongest challenge to this established liritish empiricist tradition and^ 
Indeed, to any other philosophical tradition that has an epistemologi- 
cal theory at its centte- But it may also be the ease that one reason for 
the prominence gained by Wittgenstelnian writers In the field of the 
philosophy of religion is that Qie implications of the Wittgenstelnian 
critique of epistemologieal systems may be seen to be more effective in 
this realm than in any other branch ol philosophy. And there may even 
he a straightfonvard reason for this, particularly when Wittgenstein's 
thinking is placed against the backgiound of British empiricism. For^ 
more than any other system, an empiricist epistemoIog\' has difficulty 
in accommodating claims to a knowledge of God- Even in its traditional 



122 Fmitiwphy ofRi^iisfou m the 21 it Century 



mildest form^ as we find it^ say^ in LockCn empiricist b-eliefs are iicvei 
easily fcconcitcd wtLh religious belief- despite Lockers own claim that 
Christianity Is to bo embraced on account of its 'reasonabkn^ss'. Tbe 
gap between the claim abouE what can be know^n with certainty 
through sensation and reflection on the erne hand, and Ihe claim lo 
know a transcendent DeiEy ^vhom no man hath seen', on the other 
handj ahvays has to be bridged within an empiricist eptstcniologicaJ 
l^ramcT.-vork. And that bridge has never been satisfactorily or consis- 
tently constructed. The recourse to some alleged experiences, such as 
that of a 'leap of faith' or of some "intuitive disclosures^ docs not dose 
the Rap between experiences of an empirical nature and knowledge of 
a God that iSj in some sense^ ^beyond' this visible^ tangible Avorld- And 
neither is, in my view, what appears to be a more consistent position 
from an empiricist standpoint, the claim that, on the basis of evidence^ 
the tmth of the belief in God is a matter of high probability^ religiously 
satisfactory cither Of course, empiricism In its most virulent fomin leads 
either to a Hume-type form of scepticism or, to an equally pernicious 
fotm of seientLsni such as that fostered by Logical Positivism from the 
1930s onwards. In the second half of this century, both forms of 
empiricism^ the mild and the vitulent, have still exercised considerable 
infiucncCr and I think that it is correct to say that the English have 
remained true to wliaL is^ primarily, their tradition- And it is against the 
background of a long- standings resistant Tiritish empiricism that one 
must, at least Ln part, assess the contribution of the later Wittgenstein 
to the philosophy of religion- 

The emancipation of the philosophy of rcligioti from the constraints of 
an empirical epistcmological sj^tcm was not Wltt^nstcin's only contri- 
bution lo the philosophy of religion. Of greater importance w-as his insis- 
tence on the indeterminate nature of the criteria of intelligibility- In the 
Tmntatiis, Wittgenstein had attempted to lay down a single, absolute 
measure of the distinction between sense and nonsense. But in the 
Philamphicui Investigutions, it is maintained that it Is not always that 
easy to distinguish beti^'een sense and nonsense - and this is partly the 
case because of the complcjtity of that distinction. In the Piiilasaphla^l 
Ifivestig^itionSf language is inextricably connected with our livings with 
our day-to-day practices. The speaking of language Is part of an activ- 
ity, or a form of life' (RL, para 23). Hence, understanding language 
means understanding what is going on - and vice versa. What it makes 
sense to say, or not to say, depends on what is the precise nature of the 
activity under consideration^ And if our practices are so diverse and. In 
principle, without any predetermined Ix^uiidarics (as, for instance, old 



Wafforti GeaSy iz:i 



practices cease to be and arc replaced by novel ones, and so there arc 

constantly new ways of speaking while others hecome obsolete], then the 
criteria of the intelligibility are equally indeterminate. The boundaries 
of inlelligibilily are in a constant slale of flux. The expression^ This 
lan^agc game Is played' encapsulates^ possibly most directly^ the new 
freedom from the traditional kind of externally imposed, rigid, single 
crtterlon of meaning - the kind of criterion that had been adopted by 
philosophers in the past - with the inevitable consequence of artificially 
limiting the possibilities of langnage. This does not mean Ihat, accord- 
Lng to Ihe Piiiiosop!ui:ai Iffvejitigi^tiofis, miythiff^ goes - for there bolh are 
standards within activities that detemiine what is meaningful and w^hat 
Is not. Uutj also^ of paramount iniportance is the fact ihat the aclLvitles 
themselves are related to eacli otiier in a variety of w^ays. They form a 
'complicated netw^ork' and, as a consequence, they have a bearing on 
each other. In this sense^ the intelligibility of one way of saying some- 
thing Is related to the intelligibility of other ways of speaking. No single 
activity, completely isolated from others, wotild be intelltgible. Now 
there may be all sorts of aberrations or distortions of correct practices^ 
which would be deemed false or foul or unreasonable practices, and 
they would be determined to be such in terms of either the standards 
internal to the practices themselves ^rby bemg shown to be incompat- 
ible with standards of a related practice or practices ^u^ both- it is impor- 
tant to underline that practices are not isolated from each other, for its 
neglect can lead to all sorts of confusion. That language games have 
their owti identity is important too - for if it were not for such an iden- 
tity it would be meaningless to speak of relationships. But all the prac- 
tices form part of 'the stream of life' - a complex, but indetcrtninateH 
cultural whole. What we have^ accordmg to Wittgenstein^ is a compli- 
cated network of similarities overlapping and criss-crossing: sometimes 
overall similarities^ sometimes similarities of detail/ (RL, para 66} 

Those preoccupied with religious matters, and theolo^ans In particu- 
lar, who had been condemned by the Logicat Positivisits as confused 
babblers, have felt emancipated as a result of the Impltcatlons of 
Wittgenstein's new understanding of tl:ie conditions of intelligibility. It 
Is for this reason that one wants to say that no one tn this century no 
one perhaps at any timen has done a greater ser^^ee to the philosophy of 
religion - for, it seems that, at no other time in the histori.^ of Western 
philosophy, had religion beeti under such an acute attack as It was from 
those professional practitioners of philosophy earlier in this centuryn 
who had condetnned religious language as meaningless. And, by now, 
over fifty years after those initial pernicious attacks on religion^ it Is often 



124 Flrihiwphy ofRi^Hsfou in the 21 it Century 



claimed ihat the phUosophy of religion has undergone a renaissance, par- 
Ucularly in the English-speaking world. If this is [rue, as I believe it is, it is 
in no small measure, a direct coniequcnce of the new life breathed into it 
by tlie implications of Wittgenstein's later philosopliy. 

This was an issue that 1 had wished Mutliall would have said more 
about. But he may liave taken all tliis for granted. Yet, the impression 
1 liave from his paper is titat Wittgenstein's sole contribution to philoso- 
phy IS his method for clearing up conceptual contusion. This is a view 
that is widely in vogue. Of course, It is an important part of Wittgetv 
5tein^s legacyj and tlie significance of this contribution is not to be 
underestimated. U is also true that, in the final part of liis paper, Mulhall 
does refer to ^the transformation and enrichment that VVillgenstein^s 
grammatical reminders can engender' - and he is even critical of Winch's 
attempt to impose limitations on this cnrichmeni! Yet, in the paper 
itself; there is very little development of what this enrichment might 
mean in the realm of religion. In most of his essay^ Mulhall is content 
to underlh^e the significance of the innovation that religious proposi- 
tions are different from empirical propositions. But this is not to say 
much. It is a negative thesis. It says nothing positive, for instance, 
about the kind of language that religious language itself is. Xoi that w^e 
find much of that in Wittgenstein eichcL However^ b}^ emphasizing the 
indeterminacy of the logic of language, Wittgenstein was drawing our 
attention to the richness and diversity of human experiences. Having 
succeeded in casting off the strailjackel of a single, rigid but artificial 
criterion of meaning, Wittgenstein allow^ed language to be itself in 
all its diversity, richness and splendour. He waiited to show language as 
it Is and also the possibilities of language that enable us to see things in 
a variety of new and different ways. Logical fotmalistn with its tigidity 
is banished and in its place we have diversity, fluiditv^, imagination and 
creativity. It is in the opening up of these possibilities, in showing us 
how human practices may be understood in different w^ays, that one 
can claim that no one has contributed more in recent timcSj indirectly, 
to the philosophy of religion. 

Now^ let us turn to what appear to me to be some difficulties in 
Wittgcnstein^s thinking about religious matters, Not that 1 wish to 
suggest that everything in this field that belongs to him is problematic- 
But 1 have found certain aspects of the contents of the three lectures 
on religious belief (as they are found In the LC) quite unacceptable- 
Some of Wittgenstein's remarks, in this specific context appear both 
strange and confused - this, again^ often in stark contrast lo many of 



the numerous {ni f-mc religious remarks found scattered elsewhere in his 
writings. There are three basic points that I wish to make about these 
LC lectures on religious belief. First, there are philosophical difficulties 
here which are connected with the way Wittgenstein presents liis case: 
tlie disjunction bct^vecn tlie religious and the empirical is overstated 
and is far too figid. Secondly, and this is a matter of some conjecture, 
these difficulties may be related to problems which Wittgenstein might 
have felt at that time (around 1938), and w-hich arose directly from 
his novel thinking on logic. And, finally; there seem to me to be insu- 
perable difficulties with wiiat may described as Wittgenstein's 'theol- 
ogy', as it is reflected in the examples given in the LC of religious 
assertions. 



Perhaps it is something of a surprise that someone who espouses 
Wittgenstein's later philosophy should find aspects of his thought in 
the LC unacceptable. Why is this the case? Is not Muthall perfectly 
correct when he states that the whole of Wittgenstein's eiiterprise in 
the LC has to do with highlighting the differences between empirical 
statements and religious statements? And is not this emphasis^ on 
showing differences, wholly in character with Wittgenstein's tliesis in 
the PJuIosop!ikiii Inve^^ti^atiofi!^? ft is readily conceded that the whole 
burden of Wittgenstein's later logic was 'to show differences' between 
different ways of speakings or of language uses. He wished to destroy 
the kind of false unity that he has ascribed to language in Lhc Tractiftns 
by making that unity formal - 'the common or general form of propo- 
sition', liut, as it has already been suggested, the poinE of referring to 
different language games was to show^ that 'saying something' differs 
from context to contextj from one acUvliy to another. But, in the LC, 
at this comparatively early stage In the development of the later thesiSn 
there are dangers inlierent in the way Wittgenstein presented his case, 
and these may be partly responsible for much of the confusion that Is 
often seen in the writings of Witigensteinian philosophers of aeligionn 
and particularly the charge that their standpoint is fideistic. 

What we are presented with in the LC is a dichotomy - betw^een two 
ways of speakfng, between the empirical and the religious. It may be 
askedj ''Why only two?^ Is our speakings our language, divided in such a 
dichotoraous way? Granting that it was Wittgenstein's intention to 
demonstrate the distinctiveness of a religious way of speaking, why did 



126 Flrihiwphy ofRi^Hstou m the 21 it Century 



he ground it on a single comparison? And why did that comparison 
have to be based on differences Tviih empirical proposHions? Would 
not^ and docs not such a contra-st immediately and inevitably remind 

us of the Tractatiis duatisin? My impression is that the Tyiictntus casts a 
heavy shadow on Ihe LC. Tliis may be discerned in Ihe Avay Wittgenstein 
proceeds to make the distinction between Hicsc two ways of speaking, 
and especially by the kind of language that he uses to make and 
describe the distinction, h is not thaL one questions tlie validity of the 
distinction itself between the empirical and the religious, but the lan- 
guage that is used echoes clearly earlier ideas. If one may adopt and 
adapt one of Wittgenstein's later analogies of language - that of a city 
without a high road - what we have in the Tnictntns was, not so much 
a city but a single throughfare. In the LC, we do haA'e a cirVp but one 
that docs have a high road - and thai is the thorougiifare we had in 
the Tnicti2t{is. This high road In the LC is there variously alluded to^ 
and described, as 'the normal', 'the ordinary everyday\ and 'the rea- 
sonable'. In the first of the three lectures alone, the terms normal', 
■"ordinar)^ everyday' and ^reasonable' are used on numerous occasions, 
and on each of these the purpose is to contrast such a way of speaking 
with tlic religious way of speaking_ I do not think for a monicnl thai 
the author of the Phiiosophkal Investigations would have jx>rtrayed mat- 
ters in this way There clearly language is portrayed as a city without a 
high road. Naturally, if only two things arc sharply contrasted "with 
each other, inevitably a dichotomy is created. But wiiat is objectionable 
in the LC is that the one side of the dichotomy is exclusively identified 
with 'the ordinary^ 'the normal' and 'the rcasonablc'j and hence mark- 
ing It distinctly as the hi;^h road. That cannot but be highly reminls- 
eetil of the Tmctutm position - except, of course, that now the religious 
way is accepted as intelligible. But merely by describing one w^ay of 
speaking as 'normar^ ''ordinary^ 'everyday' - even without identifying 
the precise nature of that way - V%^ittgen stein has, perhaps unwittingly, 
relegated uU other ways of speaking to a suburban status in our lives- 
In the Tractiitiis, religious discourse was altogether outside the world, 
outside the city in the LC, this way of talking is just somewhere within 
the city's periphery. Furthermore^ by formulating the dichotomy in the 
way he does, Wittgenstein creates the impression that what he refers to 
as ^the ordinary everyday^ way of speaking is a single or unified way of 
speaking - and that it stands in stark contrast with the religious way of 
speaking. It is an odd city indeed, with one major thoroughfare, and 
one distant side road wliieh at no point intersects with that thorough- 
fare. How different this image is from that created in the L*!iiiosaphka! 



Wafforti GeaSy 127 



Investigations where there is insistence on both diversity of ways of 
speaking and on their relalcdncss! 

The manner then in which Wittgenstein mak^s and sustains his dis- 
tinction between the empirical and the religious in the LC implies that^ 
from a certain standpoint caHcd 'normal', 'ordinary" and 'reasonable'^ 
religions beliefs are to be thought of as being entirely outside these 
categories. Prima facie^ it would appear that the Implication is that 
such religious Ixlicfs are abnormal, extra-ordinary and even unreason- 
able. Indeed, be explicitly states of religious believers, 'I would say that 
they are certainly not rcasonablCj that's obvious/ Uul then he proceeds 
to remark^ '"Unreasonable" implies, with everyone, rebuke.' And clearly 
Wittgenstein docs not, for logical reasons, wish to describe religious 
belief as 'unreasonable'. But he does want to say that religious belief is 
not within the realm of reason, hi the Tmctah^s, religion is not in the 
realm of the intelligible- In the LC religion is not in the realm of reason. 

Again, there are strong reasons for believing that the Wittgenstein of 
the Philosophkal Inve^ti^nthms would not have expressed himself in this 
way. HerCj in the LC^ he seems to adopt an esscnttalist conception of 
'reason'^ which is synonyinous with 'tt:ie ordinary" and ^the usual'. Not 
that his reniarks appear thoroughly consistent in the LC. For, as Mulhall 
points out, the distinction which Wittgenstein makes al one point 
between 'reasons' aiid 'normal reasons' (LQ p- 56) suggests that tliere are 
different kinds of reasons. Yet, w^hat a strange distinction and dichotomy 
again[ Are reasons that are not ^normal reason^ to be thought of as 
abnormal? What would that mean? But the concession that there are 
different kinds of reasons does at least reflect a position w^hich Is 
slightly closer to that which we find in the Fiuhsophkat Tm^esti^nthns. 
What he ought to liave maintained here is that which he made clear in 
his later writings - that there arc multiple criteria of 'reason' or 'ratio- 
nality'- fiutn here in the LC he proceeds to say: '1 want to say: they (that 
is, religious believers) don't treat this as a matter of reason ability' - a 
remark which is patently false. This, it seems to me^ reflects an cssen- 
tlalist conception of rationality, which is completely incompatible with 
Wittgenstein's later thinking. 

Unfortunately^ Wittgenstein goes on to attempt to fortifj^ his claim 
by makji:ig the remark: 'Anyone who reads the Epistles will find it 
said: not only that it is not reasonable, but thai it is. folly' (LC, p. SS). 
Wittgenstein's exegesis of the Biblical text is patently wrong. The mis- 
take he first seems to make is connected with the logical point that I 
wish to underline. In the text, to w^iidi I assume Wittgenstein is refer- 
ring (1 Cor 1)h it is the reiigious unbeliever that calls the religious beliefs 



12fi Flrihiwphy of fi^/ij^i^n p;i the 21 it Century 



in question foolishness'. But to those who believe in the Christian faith, 
Tvhat they believe in - that is, rcdcnipilon through the cross of Christ - 
expresses the very wisdom of God. Of course, this wisdom is very 
different horrid and contrasts sharply wilh 'the wisdom of the wise' - 
(although, it would be a massive error to understand this wisdom here 
as something which is synonyTnous with "^the emptri€al\ The issue 15 
essentially religious and concerns salvation. Is salvation through man's 
own wisdom or through divine grace?) Uut there is a huge gap between, 
on the one hand, recognizing that there arc different kinds of wisdom 
or 'reason ability' and niaintainingj on the othei hand, that btlicvers 
don't treat their beliefs 'as a matter of reasonabiIit5*'^. Or that believers 
■"don^t use reason here^ as Wittgenstein remarks. To extradite himself 
from his confusion at this level all that he needed to say is what St Paul 
himself w^as mahitalning in this context, not that wisdom is one thing, 
]tut that God^s wisdom is entirely different from 'the wisdom of the 
wise'. Indeed, had Wittgenstein followed strictly the apostle's reason- 
ing, then he would have been led to say something that is to some 
degree more in agreement with his Philosophkcii Im^stigation.-^' view\ 
namely that these two forms of wisdom are wholly different from each 
other. For not only is the logo5 of the cross foolishness to those who do 
not believe^ but It is also the case that God is said to pronounce the 
'wisdom of the wise' to be 'foolishness'. 

Now is ^the normal', 'the ordinary' everyday' therefore, to be deemed 
to be outside this divine reasonabletiess? Ihis question Is merely indica- 
tive of the absurdity of the strict dichotomous way that Wittgenstein 
has presented his case Indeed, Wittgenstein^s error is even deeper than 
what has already been suggested. For the 'wisdom of the wise\ in the 
Scriptural context, is not contrasted at ah, as Wittgenstein has wrongly 
assumed, w'ith a n on -religious form of wisdom, but with a rival form of 
religious wisdom. For if the "'wisdom of the w^ise' Is at all at variance 
with 'di\1ne wisdom' both forms of wisdom are within the complex of 
religious lliought^ and are essentially at odds with eacli other on the issue 
of human salvation. In the relevant Scriptural text, both the Jew^s and the 
Giecks seek salvation in one way or another. Uiit the wise, we arc told, 
h^n^e fiiiied it^ thcsr efforts to kuow God through their wisdom - and 
Uiat, we are told, is as a result of divine wisdom. They have failed 
therefore, in what is an essentially religious quest - that of saIvaMon„ 
The whole text and its reasoning has nothing whatsoever to do with 
anything like 'empirical evidence' or Verification' and Ihc connection 
bctu^een such concepts and tlie logic of propositions. Wittgenstein has 
completely misunderstood the tcxtl 



Wafforti GeaSy 1Z9 



My second point is this. I believe that some of Ihe difficullies I find with 
tliese lectures may be connected with tlie fact thai what wc have here 
belongs to an inleini&diary period In the deTL^elopment of Wittgenstein's 
later philo-sophy- VVillgcnslein was constantly reviewing^ modifying and 
developing his position^ and the thinking reported in these lectures 
docs not reflect the implicalions for religion of Wiltgenstein^s more 
mature standpoint as wc have it^ say, in the PhUosophical iRVt'sti^nthms, 
or In Oiij Ct'itiiif^t}'. These lectures on religious belief were delivered in 
I95ft- The Blue ^ifhi Broiwj Books, which contain the earliest versions of 
Witlgenstein's later philosophy;, were notes of lectures delivered in the 
academic years 1933/4 and 1934/S respectively. The notes contained in 
tlie Browji Book were revised in 1936. Yet^ despite the fact that these two 
books of notes arc only separated by a short gap in timCj there appear to 
be, as kush Rhces explains in the Preface to these hooks, suhslantial 
modifications in Wittgenstein's views - in the way Wittgenstein speaks 
of language games, for instance. And there are differences again when 
we come to the PhiIo^opSm'{iI hivestigiitions itself. These differences are 
not peripheral cither, but belong to ccntial nolions in Wittgenstein's 
later thinking. They are connected with the whole question of the 
nature of the unity of language and the intei relations hips helween vari- 
ous ways of thinking - Issues which also have a direct bearing on our 
understanding of the logic of religious propositions. 

This may help us to explain wliy Wttgenstem underlined in such a 
rigid way the distinction between the empirical and the religious. Indeed, 
the rigidity of his position suggests that although he liad rejected the 
formalism of llie Trrtrf^ah/i he had embraced a new fornialism - one that 
allowed for diversity in terms of multifarious language gameSj but now 
these forms of language have a rigidity of their own and are wholly 
autonomous. Tliere seems to he nothing whatsoever in common 
between the empirical and the religious. Every way of speaking is dis- 
tinct. Everything again^ it seems^ must be crystal clear! Logic demands 
it! Again^ J am suggesting that the Tractatus casts its shadow on the way 
the dichotomy between the empirical and the religious Is presented in 
tlic LC. This is even more understandable also at this stage because 
Wittgenstein at this lime might st[ll have been wrestling with difficul- 
ties connected with liis novel reasoning. For his new logic led 
inevitably to the acceptance of realities other than simply the one real- 
ity that is 'pictured^ by the empirical sciences. Did not his new think- 
ings therefore, lead to the acceptance of Ihe reality of God? And did this 
mean that he had lo embrace this reality? I suspect that Wittgenstein 
must have Ikcu troubled by these questions. They might have appeared 



130 Fmitiwphy ofReii^ou m the 21 it Century 



lo him as rather unfortunate consc<]ucnccs of his novel view that the 
crttcria of intclligLbility arc intcrrval to liuman practices- They ccitainly 
presented a challenge- For religion, after ail^ is not a universally 
embraced form of life - like, say^ the language of (alklng about ph^^ical 
objects, or the language of mathematics, or even moral language. All 
these forms of discourse evidently have an unquestioned rcahly of 
tlieir own. But religion? Tt would seem that the most effective strategy 
Wittgenstein could adopt, to extradite him from Lhis logical dilemma, 
would be precisely ihe one that we find in the LC - that is, the strategy 
of underlining th^l rdl^ion is so different from the 'ordinary' or 'the 
reasonable' that it is not a matter of reasonableness at all to embrace it. 
On the contrary, religion is a matter of passionate belief without rea- 
son. All this^ I admit is a matter of conjecture on my part. But I am 
looking for possible reasons Avliy WiLtgenstein created such an 
unbridgeable gulf bet^veen the empirical and the religious- 

It is no wonder ihat, partly as a result of the use by Wittgenstein of such 
expressions as 'they (religious believers) are not reasonable - meaning they 
don't use re^ison hcre^ VViltgcnstcinians have been labelled "'fideisls'. If 
religious believers do not use reason, then they arc fideists. They liave 
faith 'without reason' - and what kind of faith is that? Mulhall dis- 
cusses this issue in the second part of his paper. 1 suspect that the pri- 
mary reason why tidclsm has been condemned by most Christian 
theologians is because tliey are rightly suspicious of emotfon. And the 
Scriptures^ in one of the most famous parables in the New Testament, 
that of the sower^ warn against a faith that Is based upon an emotional 
response. Emotions, we are advised^ arc fleeting and cannot withstand 
the trials and tribulations of life- As the strength of the emotion dimin- 
ishes, so the faith disappears with iL Historically, of course^ fidcism has 
been connected with the rejection of natural theology, and natural 
tlieology has l>ccn seen as an external justification of religion through 
■"the natural light of reason' - w^hatever that means- If we base our 
assessment of Wittgcnstein^s position fp these issues solely on the basis 
of what we find in the LC, then, in my view, he is rightly accused of 
being fidcistic- However, in the light of the l^ihsophiaii hivestigtitioiis, 
this view has tc be radically revised- For if Tideisra' simply means 'faith 
without reason" then religion, like all other meaningful practices, has 
its internal rules that determine what does, and what does not, make 
3cnse- As Rhecs once put it: Theology is the j^rammar of religious 
belief/ Furthermore, as it has already been emphasized, Wittgenstein 
in the PSiShsophkiii lui^estigiitiom insisted that oui ianguage-games' are 
related to each other - and it is because our practices are related to 



Wafforti GeaSy 131 

each other that they arc intelligible in our lives, kcligion is not ati 
exception and licnce Is not fldeistlc in terms of the Phiio^opiiical l!ive.^ti- 
gathf^s criteria - if ^fidcism^ means ^faith without reason'. 

4 ■ 

However, tf fideisni means Taith not based on reason^ Wittgenstein's 
position is more complex. For he argues ihat our language games are not 
based on anything. Indeed, the whole meaning of tlie expression 'the 
natural light of reason^ on ivhich^ according to traditional natural theol- 
ogy, faith is supposed to rest, becomes meaningless - for it implies that 
there is some rationality that is independent of, or transcends the par- 
ticular practices in our lives. But, againj our reasons arc internal to the 
activities: each 'game' has its own rules. This is the way we count. 
These are our moral values. This is the way we speak alx>ut physical 
objects. This is our religious faith. In each instance^ in each 'form of 
life'' or activity, we use reason - or rather wt reason in different ways. 
What then becomes of natural theology? Docs this mean that it is 
necessarily meaningless? It Is possible to understand the arguments of 
natural theology in a different way- not as some proofs of faith based 
on considerations external to the realm oi faith^ hut rather as exercises 
in the grammar of faith - and as bridges that may be used to attempt 
to relate the language of faith to otiier forms of discourse. For instance, 
without the theology of ^revealed religion^ which contains references 
to 'the eternity of God^ that lie is 'from everlasting to everlasting', the 
Ontological argument would have no meaning at all. Similarly, if it 
were not for the religious helief in the goodness of God as Creator^ 
both the Teleological and the Cosmological arguments w^ould be reli- 
giously worthless. For the idea of everything depending on son'jc 
impersonal Cause is a religiously futile idea. What the believer seeks Is 
not a causal explanation of existence, but rather the assurance that 
existence is essentially good and, hcneen meaningful Statural theologv^ 
is not a matter of making inferences from the world, from outside 
faith, to God, but rather it Is an attempt to show how, from the stand- 
point of faith, the world is perceived. 



Thirdly, let us turn to Wittgenstein's 'theology'. There is something 

profoundly wrong with Wittgenstein ^s characterization of religious 
beliefs in the iC. What we are presented with here are religious beliefs 
as caricatures of empirical hypotheses and predietions. Again, the 
Influence of the T^^jhihis is undeniably evident. In the Tmctiitii^, only 
propositions which belong to the natural sciences have sense, Tn the 



132 Pffiio.wphy ofRi^iisfou Ui the 21 it Century 

LCf only the propositions %vhich arc supported by c\adGricc arc reason- 
able. If you make predictions, say aboui the wealher or about the 
strength of the pound sterling in a year's time, you may he asked to 
justify your belief in terms of cerlaiii evidence. The prcdicUons may be 
said to be reasonable or unreasonable depending on the evident^ or 
weight of probai^ility. And, evidently, if you make predictions without 
reference to any evidence, that is clearly an example of irrationality. 
Now, it is significant to note that almost every example provided by 
Wittgenstein of a religious belief has a form which resembles a predic- 
tion. They arc supposed to be religious utterances Ijut they have the 
appearance of empirical predictions - with this cruciaE difference. They 
appear to be without evidence and thus totally baseless. I Icnce^ the^^ 
have the appearance eo being wholly irrational This is Wittgenstein's 
ground for saying that they are 'not reasonable'. N'ow consider the fol- 
lowing examples of ^religious^ remarks made by Wttgensteln in this 
context: 



T shall think of you after my death, if that should be possible^ 
'Suppose someone believed in the Last judgement/ 
■"Suppose ...another says, 'No. Particles will join together ina tliousand 
years, and there will be a Resurrection of you/ 

T believe that so and so will happen ../ 

'What we call belie\1n^ in a Judgement Day or not believing in a 

Judgement Day.-/ 

'Suppose someone dreamt of the Last Judgement.-, and said to 

me .-.' 'It will be in about 2000 years ../ 

'Dead undergraduate speaks../ 

'He said that this was^ m a way, proof of the immortality of the soul.' 



'Deaili'^ 'speaking after death', 'immotiallLy of the souF^ 'Last Judge^ 
ment', 'Judgement Day'. "'Resurrection' - these concepts reappear time 
and time again in Wittgenstein's remarks on religion in this context- 
And this Is profoundly misleading In two respects- First, these examples 
aie formulated ii:L such a way, deliberately or out of sheer ignorance, to 
appear as predictions. The references to 'a thousand ycars^ and '1000 
years' reinforces this view^ Yet, in a profound sense, such allusions to a 
lime-scale make them clearly pseudo-religious rci^iarks - remarks which 
one normally associates with w;eiid and superstitious cults. Secondly, 
they are given such, almost exclusive, prominence by Wittgenstein in 
diis context, that the impression is created tiiat they are, is some sense, 
typical of religious beliefs and central to the religion that is being 



WGffGTii Ge^ly ISA 

characterized- liut^ they are certainly not concepts that arc central in 
Christian l:kclicf. On the contrary, religious believers that give such 
prominence to e^chatological ideas in their thinking are normally asso- 
ciated with peripheral^ heterodox sects or cults that ^cem to appear and 
disappear as regularly as their false predicliotisJ Wittgenstein's preoccu- 
pation wilh such examples is grossly unfortunate and betrays a sad 
inLsunderstanding of the Christian faith- This is not the place to dis- 
cuss the meaning ot" Christian eschatology, Imt it is at least meaningful 
to ask whether or not these doctrines arc, in any sense, connected with 
timCj or whether any cschatological beliefs arc essentially concerned 
with hjture events. There are some Christian theologians who advocate 
a belief in 'a realized eschatology^j that is, the Judgement Day is ever- 
present. Mowever, even if these examples given by Wtugenstein are to 
be regarded as some kind of predictions, then they are religious predic- 
tions made within a religious conceptual frame^^^ork, This would make 
them not unlike, say, an Old Testament prophet's prediction that 
Jenjsalem would fall to an eitemy attack. Such predictions were made^ 
not because the prophets had some paranormal view of the fut jre^ but 
simply because they believed the words of the divine covenant. God 
would visit his people for their sins. The 'given^ here is a belief in a 
divine covenant. It was believed that what happened to the nation was 
wholly predictable - for its fate depended on its obedience or disobedi- 
ence to the Law of the covenant- Such predictions, within tliat concep- 
tual framework^ were nol at all unreasonable^ but were expressions of 
the prophets' religious reasoning and faith. 

Yet in the LC context^ whatever thtse beliefs meann they are said to 
be unconnected with evidence. This, apparently^ is partly what ^ives 
them their religious character and gives them the appearance of being 
outside the category of the 'reasonable'. I do not beheve that the 
Wittgenstein of the Fhiloscpiiiaii InvL'stigiitioiis would liavc ever main- 
tained this ar^mentn for as it stands, it is a^ain contaminated by a 
form of essentialisni. It is as if ^evidence' can only be one thing. But if 
we speak of different language games and practices, we may also speak 
of different kinds of evidence, and not only of evidence as we have it In 
science, or in 'everyday beliefs^ as referred to in the LC Wittgenstein^s 
whole argument militates against the language of the Christian Scrip- 
tures, in which constant reference is made to 'witnesses* ^testifying' to 
the truth of their claims. For instance^ one of tl:te central concepts in 
the Fourth Gospel is that of 'witnesses' who ^testify' to the divinitj' of 
Jesus. Again, this is not to idenLify the evidence of such witnesses with 
what we call ^empirical evidence'. That would be wholly mistaken. The 



134 Flfiitiwptiy ofRi^fi^ou m the 21 it Century 



conceptual framework of ^JGW Tcstainent-limc observers that made it 

possible for ihcin to 'sec" God in Jesus is radically diffcrcnl from the 
conceptual framework that enables us to forecast tomorrow's weather 
or to see that inflationary pressures within tlie economy will affect the 
value of money in a year's lime. But that does not mean that the 
concept of evidence is to be proscribed within religious language. That, 
iiidecd, would be a piece of philosophical dogmatism' 

ll seems to me thai an aspect of Wittgenstein's error in this context is 
to transgress one of his own more important lessoi^s in the Philo^ophi' 
cai Im^sti^utions - never to divorce assertions from their context. What- 
ever is meant by the eschatologlcal concepts he so frequently referred 
to^ they cannot be alienated from the central concepts of divinity as 
they are understood within the Christian religion. The religious povert)' 
of the LC, as reflected in the examples of religious beliefs provided, is 
startling. There is nothing at all here about those things which are 
unequivocally definitive of the Christian religion, such as, divine 
mercy, forgiveness, love and compassion. Wittgenstein's version of 
ChrLstianity is one that is cEothed in, wliat appears to be^ absurd pre- 
dictions- It Is a travest}!^ of the Christian faith. 

If there arc difficulties with VViiigensteisi's eschatoIo;^ieaI remarks 
there arc comparable difficulties also with his remarks about the role of 
historical propositions. And, at appears to me, that this Is crucial. The 
interrelationships between various forms of life constitute an essential 
condition of their intelligibility. The language games whose truths are 
those most closely related to the Christian religion are moralitj^ and 
history- Not that religious truth is idenLlcal w-ith cither of these, but 
there is a close relationship between them. (Unfortunately^ there is 
very little about morality in the LC Wittgenstein does suggest one eon- 
nection betw^cen religion and moralit;^' when he refers to the fact that 
denying the existence of God is seen as 'something bad'j and he proba- 
bly would have also understood the notion of ^divine judgemenf in 
some moral sense.) But Wittgenstein does raise the issue of historical 
truth, again in conjunction w^ith the role of evidence in our thinking. 
He admits that, even in relij^aon. 'we do talk of evidence, and do talk of 
evidence by experience. We could even tall; of historical events. It has 
been said that Chnstianlly rests on an historic basis-' What follows 
these remarks in the LC, and indeed, the way that Mulhall also deals 
with these issues, appears to me to be fundaiiientally wrong both In 
terms of logic aiid in religious terms. The issues have to do with the 
relationship between the historical and the religious. Here, however, 



we need to restrict the sense of 'religious' to the Biblical reli^^toiis - for 
bolli the religions of llie Old and New Tcstamenls claim a certain 
unique relationship with historical claims - a relationship which has 
been widely cither denied or mi ^understood since the middEe of the 
last century. Certainly, Christianity makes the claim (and 1 believe this 
is also true of Judaism), that it would be false if certain alleged histori- 
eal events did not take place. [In Judaism this is connected with the 
Exodus expcrieiice or deliverance of the Hebrew people from slavery in 
Egypt. The identity of both the jewisli God and his people are bound 
with this event. J In Chrislianityj the historical is connected with cer- 
tain events in the life of Jesus and, in particular, the claim that he was 
raised from the dead. ""If Christ tae not raised^ then is our preaching 
vain, and your faith is also vain. Yea, we are found false witnesses of 
God' (A.V-1 Col IS). In other words, Cluistian tulh and histoacal 
trutli are here so closelv interwoven that the historical truth has l>ecome 
at least oiPc^ condltloii of tlie truth ot the religious. There Is nothing com- 
parable to this in the LC. Tnsteadn what wc fiitd are ambiguous com- 
ments. Wittgenstein introduces a strange, unclear distinction between ^a 
belief in historic facts' and a belief in ordinary historic facts'. A distinc- 
tion could not be more ambiguous. But let us suppose that he had in 
inind, when referring to ^a belief in historic fact', something as extraor- 
dinary as a claim that the historical Jesus was raised Irotn the dead. 
Then, Wittgenstein inaintains, belief iii this claim is very different 
from a belief in an ""ordinary histofical fact' - like, say^ some facts about 
Napoleon. \"V^itt^en stein's point seems to be that in the latter case^ it 
is^ in principle^ possible to express doubts about what happened to 
Napoleon^ while, even though what happened to Jesus is so extraordi- 
nary, and so vasdy remoter in time than what happened to Xapoleon, 
no doubts arc ever entertained about those liistoric facts' that are at 
the heart of Christian doctrines. Propositions about Jesus 'are not 
treated as historicaln empirteal, propositions'. There Is a problem with 
bolh the generality of this remark and also with its ambiguity. Its gen- 
erality suggests either that iwifwig about Jesus is treated as eitlier his- 
torical or empirical - or that propositions about lilin are never drought 
of in historical or empirical terms - or both, nothing and never. All 
three generalizations are patently incorrect. Tlie ambi^ity of the claim 
is connected with the related idcri that the truth of bolh historical and 
empirical propositions are contingent: and it is die case that when 
assertions about Jesus are treated as leU^loit}; or theoioi^ki}! assertioiiSn 
as dogma, then what happened to Jesus is not treated as 'liistorical, 



136 Fffiitiwphy ofReiistoii m the 21 it Century 



empirical^ propositions'. Contingency is inadmissible within the con- 
text of faith- Religious!)-^ speaking, wh^l happened Lo Jesus, as God's 
will, could not be otherwise, while, on the other hand, what happened 
to Napoleon is a contingcnl niatlcr. The believer claims thai there was 
divine necessity in the lite of Jesus which removes all contingencj^^ from 
it. hi a religious sense the^e propositions could nol be unLrue. But 
propositions ahout Jesus arc not always treated as dogma^ and any reli- 
gious necessity dogmatic propositions possess docs not preclude the 
possibility of asking the empirical, historical question: 'What did actu- 
ally happen to Jesus?' - in which case wc arc engaged in an empirical 
enquiry - and we may ask all sorts of questions about the historical 
authenllcity of the Gospel records, and so on. In one context therefoEC, 
what happened to Jesus Is absolutely indubitable^ while in another 
related context, that of an historical enquiry, what did actually happen 
to Jesus is still open to empirical investigation. 

Of course, it would be wrong to separate the propositions about tlie 
Jesus of history from the fact that they are propositions which form part 
of church dogma whose truth is guaranteed by a body that claims 
Infallibility. Or, If it is believed that it is not the church that is their guar- 
antor^ then the Scriptures theniselves, believed to be God'^ VVord^ guar- 
antees their truth. Hence, In this relijjtous tradition^ the truths about 
Jesus are guaranteed to be. In one w^ay or another, incontrovertible by an 
authority or authorities that claim to be absolute. Indeed, it is only after 
the questioning of these traditional authorities of faith that doubts have 
been raised about the historicity of Jesus. But the fact that such doubts 
have been seen as an attack on the very basis of the Christian faith Is 
indicative of the significance of the role of the historical in Christ I anitj;^. 

I suspect that when Mulhall argues that If believers put so much trust 
in historical truth they must be ludicrously irrational as to strain 
credibility'. He also seems to have forgotten thaL these trutlis are not 
believed in viicuo, but arc beliefs shared by a religious community - a 
eominunlty that maintains that it has its origins in these alleged his- 
torlcal events. In this context, both the concepts of 'community' and 
'continuity' are important. And altliough such concepts may have 
some role in secular history^ they do not, in that contextj have the 
same role as they have in the religious context. Mulhall writes: 'Reli- 
gious belie^^ers base matters of great moment on evidence that seems 
exceedingly flimsy by cpmparison with the corroboration they require 
before accepting claims of far less significance for their lives/ But this is 
to exclude the central function of the role of the religious community 
in the propagation of its truths - both its religious truths and those 



historLccLl truths that arc bcticvcd to be inextricably connected with the 
religious truths. Miilhall's remark would appear to carry more weight if 
he were referring say^ to the peoples of Ephesus or Corinth in the first 
century ad. Their conversion to a new faith appears more remarkahle 
as they were asked to believe in certain alleged facts that look place in 
a distant laiid, a generation or so earlier, and wilho Jt the weight of cen- 
turies of belief in such historical truths. (But is it at all correct to 
attempt to account for tlieir religious conversions while omitting alt tef- 
erenc^ to the central Ri?ality of tlieir faith? I5 it nor a religious doctrine 
that eternal life is given as a gift by God - and that the mystery of divine 
grace surrounds the whole process?} But^ nowadays, most religious 
believers are helievers in a historical, resurrected Jesus because ot their 
upbringing. Within the religiotis context, thc5c truths are regarded as 
the ^cettainties' of faith - ""certainties' that religious helievers were prob- 
ably taught before th^ry had been introduced to, say, the certainties of 
in at hematics. If^ however, the believer develops doubts alMut the valid- 
ity of his faith and asks such questions as ^Why do I continue to 
believe these truths?' the fact that he is surrounded by a cloud of living 
witnesses, that he is part of a fellowship of saints, w^ould appear to me 
to be of inestimable si^^nihcance for him. He is not an isolated believer 
wlio possesses some private beliefs, liy tjuestiomng his faith, he is ques- 
tioning the faith of his fellow-believers - the faith, probably, of those 
who mean inosl to him as persons. He belongs to a community of faith 
that claims that it has its toots in history^ and it authenticates its exis- 
tence. In part, hy demonstrating the continuity between itself and the 
Jesus of history- 



Let us [inally turn to some of the remarks which Wittgenstein made 
elsewhere in his writing, particularly those we find in Cuftmc tind Value. 
I do iiot wish to coinmeiit at any length on what is in the I'mctatus, for^ 
although such comments are often quoted by some V\^ttgensceiniaits 
when it is convenient, the remarks cannot be reconciled with anything 
that is Christian. ^God does not re\^eal himself in the w^orld/ The world' 
here may refer to ""everytbing that is the case', to 'the totality of facts' - 
expressions which have a special meaning within the Thrcffih^s thesis, but 
the import of these assertions is to place the reality of God outside intelli- 
gible language. Hence, little of religious significance can l>e deduced from 
tiic Tfijctntta. liut elsewhere in VVillgcnstein's writings, particularly in 
Ciilture ofhf Vahie we have a variety of utterances that are deeply religious- 



I3S Fmitiwphy of fif/;j7i^?r p;i the 21 it Centiiry 

In most of thciTLj WittgDnstcin rightly und^2rlillGS the rQlatLonship 
bcru^ccn r-cligious bcli^i and a p^2^son's understanding of the kind of 
life tliat she leads and the kind of character that she is. There Is a deep 
uiidcrscanditig here of the kind of experiences that can reinforce rcii- 
glous betiefn or can even lead a person to religious faith. Wittgenstein is 
correct to point out in the LC that it is often tlie case that 'tiie word 
'^God" is amongst the earliest learnt - pictures and cateciiisms^ etc.^ 
(p. 59) and this is partly the impotlance of the role of a religious tradi- 
tion re^ferred to above. Rut he also states that Tife can educate you to 
'^believing tn God^', (CV, p. 97e) that the religious unbeliever can 
come to faith through certain 'sufferings of various sorts'. 'Life can 
force this concept on us^ (ibid.) and Wittgenstein adds 'So perliaps it is 
like the concept of ''object"' - by which I suppose he means that the 
concept t>ecomes unavoidable, the coitcept becomes a fundamental 
part of a person's seeing and understanding- God becomes ^a certainty^ 
Wlien VVitcgensiein characterizes such experiences he Uivarial:kly thinks 
of man becoming deeply^ aware of his limitations, his moral limitations 
and also his inability to cope with lifers difficulties. Man can be beaten 
by circumstances and may feel that he is being destroyed by them. He 
can succumb to endless temptations w^hich lead to a sense of hopeless- 
ness and despair. In such contexts^ a person wlio has no faith may come 
to see that faith offers hope and acceptance and, through faith she may 
see new possibititles, including the possibility of sonie form of renewal 
(Of course^ it is also the case that the person who has faith may lose it 
when faced with the vicissittides of life. A traged^^ may be felt so deeply 
that tlie language of religious gratitude^ of thanking God, has become 
empty and meaningless for him or her.) in one of these contexts^ 
Wittgenstein explains why he is tempted to hcheve in the resurrection 
of Jesus- It is, perhapSj the most orthodox of Christian remarks in his 
whole writings - for here he does imply that salvation, in the Christian 
sense, is related to a belief in a relationship with the resurrected Christ 
It is not just the case that Christians are followers of the Jesus of his- 
tory who taught a certain moral code, but that they have faith, a trust, 
in a person wlio sustains them in their weaknesses and fortifies them 
tlirough grace against temptation. It is a reli;^iously wonderful passage 
and it is astonishing to find it in Wittgenstein. 



What inclines even me to believe in Christ's Resurrection? I play as 
it w^ere with the thought. - If he did not rise from the dead, then he 
is decomposed in the grave like every human being. He is deail 
afhi dt'cotuposed. In that case he is a teacher^ like any otJier & can no 



longer Jiefp: & once more wc arc orphaned & alone. And have to 
make do wlili wisdom &: ,spcculalion- It is a^ though we arc in a hell^ 
where we can only dream & shut out ot" heaven, roofed in as it 

were ...(CVj p. 38c^ 



Wittgenstein ^oes on to refer to the soul and its passions and states, 

Only J^^^^f can believe the Resuireeiion. Or: it is love that believes the 
Resurrection. One mij^ht sayr redeeming love believes even in the 
Resurrection; holds fast cvcir to the Resurrection (CV^ p. 39cj. 

The ideas and the language used here are reminiscent of Kterkegaard. 
And it is Important lo note that ihis is one reason why It is correct to 
claim that the meaning of 'believing^ in the Cliristian eontcxtn 
changes in the light of the faet that the believer believes^ first and fore- 
mostn in a person - in the living Christ - and believing in a person is a 
very different form of believing from^ say^ believing iii any theory or in 
any historical truths. To believe in a person is to say something about a 
retation^hip with that person, and in the Christian conlext, this rela- 
tionship is determined by its theology. Hence, the constant use of such 
concepts as, Tord' and 'Saviour', 'God"" which indicalc that the believer 
sees himself respectively as servant or slave of his Lord, as the one who 
lias, is, will have to l>e rescued from sin by his Savtour, and as one sees 
liis life in terms of submission to and the worship of God. It is within 
rrfaLionship that reli^ous passion is Lo be understood^ for the relation- 
ship is one of love, trust and dependence- But these passionate beliefs 
are not unconnected v%^ith the belief in One who is not 'dead and 
decomposed'- So although Kierkegaard was perfectly correct to underline 
the passionate character of religious faith, it was his error to deny that 
one condition of this faith was a behef in the tnith of certain historical 
propositions - that Jesus Is not 'dead and decomposed'. Thou will not 
suffer thine holy one to sec corruption/ (Acts Z) 



In the final part of hi^ paper, Mulhall raises cjtjestions aftout the 
l:human condition and develops an analogy, if no( something more 
than an analogy, between human sinfulness and the roots of philo- 
sopliLcal confusion- He does this in tJre context of Malcolm's now 
famous analysis of Wittgenstein's claim tliat he could not help 'seeing 



140 Flrihiwphy of fif/JgTO?j m the 21 it Century 



every pr<^lGin from a religious point of vIgv/^ and Winch's ciiticaJ 
response to Malcolm's cssaj^ Again, there is a ^rcal deal ihai is religiously 
edifying In this third part of his paper. Like Muihall, 1 very much 
approve of Winch^'s critique of Malcolm's elucidation of Wiltgen stein ^s 
comment - although, personally, I have no dear understanding at all 
of what Wittgenstein meant by this confession. There is no difficulty 
with the first part of Wittgenstein's admission that he was 'not a reli- 
gious man"" and this 1 find is easy to accept. For I do not find much 
in Wittgenstein's writings that would tempt mc to describe him as 
'religious' - parLicularly if 'religious' means 'Christian'. There is a super- 
abundance of evidence, of course, that Wittgenstein had a passionate 
concern for moral ideals and that he strove for some kind of moral per- 
fection. But that is very different from being, say, a worshipper of God 
or a man of prayer. A religious man, in the Christian sense, Is a holy 
man - a man of God, who believes and knows that 'as many as are led 
by the Spirit of God, they are the sons of God (Romans, 8). Yet, there 
are different forms and conceptions of spirituality and some of these 
may encompass Wittgenstein's religiosity. However, the problem with 
that Is that Malcolm's fouF analogies between philosophy and faith are 
based on possible parallels between Chmtkm doctrines, as understood 
by Malcolm, and Wittgenstein's philosophy. I accept in toto Mulhall's 
approval of Winch's criticisms of Malcolm. Bui ihen^ towards the very 
end of his essay, he proceeds to mate the point that there may be more 
to Malcolm's llilrd analogy than wliat Winch had appreciated. Here 
1 have failed to follow Mulhall's argument. Butj if 1 have not failed, 
then Mulhall seems to me to be confused. 

This third analogy it will be recalled, was ^betw^een the religious atti- 
tude of regarding oneself as radically imperfect or "sick", and the idea 
that philosophical puzzlement is a symptom of a 'Misease^ of our 
thinking' {RPV^ p. liOK Mjlhall interprets Wittgenstein's notion of ^the 
grammar or criteria of our ordinary words' as constituting the 'limits or 
conditions of the human capacity to know, think or speak about the 
world and the various things that are In it'. And the argument is devel- 
oped as follows. We see these limits as Limitations. Tlmliailons' implies 
imperfection and it is on this sense of imperfection that scepticism 
thrives. This scepticism is analogous with our Mnablllty or refusal to 
acknowledge the fact that human knowledge... Is necessarily condi- 
tioned'. The desire to speak outside language games is an inflection of 
the human pride to be God/ So it would seem to follow that conceptual 
confusion is cL sin - part of our degenerate nature, of 'Original Sin'. And, 
it is further argued that salvation from sin, in the religious context, is 



Wafforti GeaSy 141 



paralleled by salvation from conceptual confusion in a philosophical 
context- We need a personal rclalionshlp with Christ to save us from 
sin by his grace. We need a personal discourse with someone in philos- 
ophy to deliver tis from the 'sLn^ of conceptual confusion- 

Although 1 approve every theological remark by Mulhall, 1 believe 
that his religious enthusiasm has clouded his normal philosophical per- 
spicuity at this point. Of course, from a religious point of vicY?, any sort 
of imperfection - ph'^^ical, spiritual^ moral and intellectual amy be 
understood in terms of man's fallen nature and state- But it is equally 
the case thai in the same context^ all human goodness and perfection 
are seci:i as revealin;^ the general grace of God. But part of the difficulty 
of amalgamating such a perspective svith philosophical considerations - 
quite apart from estabhshing some identity betiveen the religious and 
the philosophical - is with the generaht)'^ of the religious assertions. 
One might argue, from a religious standpoint^ that all crime is the 
rcsutt of sin. But that belief does not in any way help us to understand 
why certain crimes are connected with, say, social or economic condi- 
tions. The general does not help us to understand the particular in this 
context- And, it seems to me, that the religious perception of universal 
human depravity does not help us to understand either the nature of 
the distinction between sense and nonsense or what conceptual clarity 
amounts to^ or what are the roots of conceptual confusion. And 1 sus- 
pect that Wittgenstein did not moan anything like what we have here 
by his admission that he saw everything from a religious point or v'iew. 

1 belie\'e that in this context^ Mulhatl has, to some degree, misrepre- 
sented some of the ideas fouiid in the Phihsopiiicnl hwestigations. First 
and foremost, he misconstrues the function of the notEon of a language- 
gamc\ As 1 tried to make it plain in my introductory remarks, my own 
conviction is that Wittgenstein introduced this notion in his work to 
fulfil two specific functions only: first, to denionsLratc the diversity and 
complexity of the criteria of intelligibility - and thus to contrast this 
view sharply with w^hat he had said in the Tra<:tiitti^ about the single^ 
general condition of intelligibility and, secondly, to underline the con- 
nection between language and human practices ot activities. In the 
Fisihsophkc^i lavciytf^ijthfis, saying something docs not always amount 
to the same thing: there is a diveisity of language games. And language 
must never be separated from our doings, from human practices, Now it 
may be correctly maintainedj as Mulhall states, that these language 
games 'constitute the limits or conditions of the human capacity to 
knoWj think or speak about the world\ Yet there are dangers here which 
arise through the use of the concepts of 'limits' and 'conditions' - for 



142 Flriitiwptiy ofReiistou m the 21 it Century 



there is a temptation to think of thesc^ particularly in the way Mulhall 
ar^es here, as bouiidatlcs ihat arc strictly set, fixed and formal And 
such a vii?w would bring U5 back to the idea of language games bcinj^ 
rigidly autonomous. Uut this is to overlook the fluid character of Ian- 
guage and practices - the fact that there is something hindamentally 
indeterminate about our practices and lives. There is constant flux. 
Constantly^ there arc new ways of saying and doing tilings, furthermore, 
what becomes of the point, emphasized by Wittgenstein, that practices 
and saving things are closely interrelated? What 1 am suggesting is that 
Mulhall misrepresents the character of the boundaries of language 
games. Again, it seems to be the case tliat we are confronted with a 
new formalism - whereas tlic thesis presented by Wittgenstein is one of 
logical informality 

When anyone is conceptually confused one ro<]t of such a confiision 
Is that we have taken a concept out of its natural setting, out of its 
grounding activity, wtEhoul realizing it, and possibly, draw wrong 
conclusions on this basis, fincfdentally this happens to all and sundry, 
and it is not only to 'competent speakers' who 'suffer such a loss of 
control when under pressure to philosophized It Is difficult to reconcile 
Ihe specific nature of the circumstances indicated here with what 
Mulhall has written Just a few lines earlier about philosophical confu- 
sion not being 'rcsuicted to inhabitants of certain disciplines'.) ITie 
confusion^ of course, is not in the taking of a word or concept out of its 
natural habitat, but the failure to realize that when we arc doing so, 
we may be usin^ the concept in an entirely neww^ay, perhaps metaphor- 
ically, or even misusing the word entirclyj and consequently drawing 
false inferences on that basis. Through extending the use of words wt 
can easily become confused. But I am at a loss to see liow such a simple 
common error ^is an inflection of the prideful human craving to be 
God\ We also make all sorts of other intellectual errors, like miscalcu- 
lating when doing mathematics, or committing the fallacy' of the undis- 
tributed middle term in a piece of syllogistic reasoning. Are these also 
aspects of our pride and depravity? Furthermore, If my language has 
gone on holiday, It may suddenly occur to me that this is the case. I 
may retrace my steps, and analyse my use of the relevant concepts, and 
save myself from conceptual confusion - without the intervention of 
either a friend or a philosopher I will have saved inyself_ But in reli- 
gious language, as Mulhall underlines, the self cannot save itself from 
its egocentricily Finally, not all my Ihinking, hopefully, is wholly con- 
fused. Uut, religiously speaking, my depravity is total - and if^ by 
chance, 1 perform any good, that is the result of the intervention of the 



grace of God: 'it is iio( I, but the grace of God that was given to me'. 

Here there is no analogy between the occasional conceptual virus that 
one^s thinking is su^cepUhk to, and the religious condition of 5ickncs5 
that leads^ without ihe iiilervcnlion of grace^ to spiritual death. 



1. L. Wittgenstein^ Phitosophkut In^'e.'itigatjoils, tr G_E_M. Anscom'he, BlackweU, 
19 5K 

Z_ Wstl^cnst^sff^ LetrhtftTi ami Convi^rsadoti.'i ofi AfnHitriks, P'iycboiogy i^ Rj^l^toji:^: 

B^itcf, ed- C Barrett^ ElackweElj i97S- 
3. L Wiltgemtein, Tfse Bliit' ^smt Bi^wf Books, 'Rl^zkweii, I97S.. 
4_ L. WittgensteEn, Cuiture imd Vt^iite, ed. G_H_ von Wright. Rt]vi?^ed Ed it if m, 

Blackwell, L993. 

5. -K. Malcx^lm, Witt^en.'^tem! {i ReSi^oiis PoitJt of Vi^w, eel. P_ Winch^ Routiedge^ 

i95;i 

6. AlE BLbJicat references are fiTjni the King James Authorized Veri^ion. 



9 



Voices in Discussion 

D.Z. Phillips 



}: III Ihc first part of what I had to say I concentrated on Wittgenstein's 
own comments on religion. In his Lectures €}i Reiigioas R^iief, he 
contrasts religious beliefs wiLh historical and cmpiiical beliefs, lie did 
this In order lo rebut misunderstandings. It is temptinR^ to think that 
you can investigate the existence cf God as though it weic a prior, 
independent belief. Wittgenstein thought this was question-begging 
because everything depends on what 'existence' means. 

In the second part of my criticism I discuss ^%^ittgensteinlanlsm. 
Here, in the prcseiice of D.Z. Phillips al Clarcmont, 1 fell I was bringing 
coals to Newcastle. I addressed the accusation of fideism, and especially 
the charge that Wittgensteinians claim IhaL religion is immune to 
criticism. It is impossible to sustain that charge, as Phillips has pointed 
out. First, there are terms of criticism wiLhin religious traditions. 
Second^ there arercligiaus responses to aspects of life that strike every- 
one- Some of these responses may be superstitious and^ hence, crlticiz- 
able. Thirdj Phillips makes use of common moral responses to criticize 
certain treatments of Lhe problem of evil Fourtli, although Philiips 
does not press this, there is the kind of criticism that Nietzsche, Freud 
and Marx made of religion. Certain forms of religion may indeed turn 
out to be unhealthy masochism, economic exploitation, social and 
poiitical oppression, or dependence on a fatiier figure. So possibilities 
of criticism are not denied by Wittgensteinians. "What is denied is that 
tlie whole of religion could be shown to he meaningless. 

The third part of my paper is the most controversial and I doubt 
whether it would be acceptable to Phillips. I try to see what Wittgenstein 
meant when he said that although he was not a religious man he could 
not help seeing every problem from a religious point of view. This 
remark is discussed by Norman Malcolm in WittgL'tutt'ln - a Rdlghns 



144 



Point of View! And by Peter Winch in his Response in that work. I do 
iiot think Malcolm's analogies bcLwcen philosophical concerns and 
religious concerns work for the reasons Winch provides, but Winch 
docs not dismiss the issue of spiritual concern in this context. But I am 
not altogether convinced of what he goes on to say, Ho says that lack 
of clarity has important consequences for life, but distinguishes, some- 
what artificially in my view, between importance for the sense of life^ 
and 'importance for the sense of one's own life'. Take as an example 
of the difference between first person and third person statements in 
the philosophy of psychology. Conceptual confusion can lead to views 
about private access; that there ^s something unique about one's 
experience that others can't have access to- BuL is it not also possible to 
live that confusion, to think Ehat one is uniqui^ beyond the reach of 
others? 1 think Winch's distinction makes it look as though there are 
difficulties which only belong to an exclusive class of people called 
philosophers, as though others were not vulnerable [o them. 

But w^hy do I think there is a genuinely religious aspect to this 
philosophical concern? First, the confusion comes from the attempt 
to speak outside all language ^ames; to speak outside the conditions 
of sense. This can be seen as a profound dissatisfaction with life, and 
aspiration to transcend the human, an impulse to go beyond it. 

Second, there Is an interesting comparison between the philosopher 
and his or her interlchcutor, and Christ and the belicver_ 1 suggest that 
there is a parallel iKtween original sin and the role Cavcll assigns to 
scepticism - the issue of what is involved in the denials of scepticism- 
Spiritual issues are involved in the denial of the human. One^s concerns 
may be philosophical^ but the motivation can be spiritual^ just aSj In 
political theory^ Rawls can advance a theory of justice, inspired by 
neutralitj^j and still be moved by a passion for justice. So 1 am suggesting 
that Wittgenstein's combating confusion can have a spiritual aspect 



Ki 1 am critical only of the third part of /^s paper. I don't object to the 
religious comments he makes there, but T do not see how he can tink 
them to a philosophical position. 

When 1 read Wittgenstein's Lectures ami Conversations T was unhappy 
from the outset. 1 listened with two ears: one philosophical^ the other 
trained by my religious upbringing. It seemed to mc that his remarks 
on religion are tied too closely to the Tn^ctiitiLS view of language- It is 
unfortunate, therefore, if defenders of Wittgenstein use these very 
retnarks as a general accoiuit of his views on jujjglon. I have in mind 
the claim that God does not reveal himself in the worlds and that the 



146 FIfiitiwphy ofReii^ou m the 21 it Century 



mystical is not how the world is^ but that it is. Rhecs in Wittgenstem mul 
the Posaihifity of Discourse says that even in the Inwstigutiom VVlUgcn- 
5tGin 15 still influenced by the analogy between language and a calculus. 
If Rhccs is rigliEj there is an interaction between language games and 
there is not the sharp distinction between the empirical and the spiri-^ 
tuai that we have in the Lectures nmi Corwersatiotis where the concepts 
of ^knowledge' and 'truth' are simply given up to the empirical realm. 
Truth and falsity belong to activities and thus when we pay attention to 
divine activities we open up an entirely new field of enquiry- 

The charge that VYittgcnstcinianism has no room for notions of 
'truth' and 'falsity' is absurd. Here arc just some examples. 

Firsts Paul argued that circumcision was not necessary to be a mem- 
ber of the Church. To think olhcrwisc, he said, was an error. Paul said 
that this was false doctrine. So this is doctrinal falsity. 

Second^ the Jews %vould condemn calling Jesus Tord^ or 'God^ To 
them this is idolatry. That is another form of falsity- 
Third, we have hypocrisy - another form of error. 

Fourlhj there is superstition- 1 had ncvcf flown before 1 came to this 
conference, 1 took my New Testament with me on the plane, 1 found 
myself wondering whelher 1 was indulging in superstition, thinking 
that the mere possession of the Testament would save me from harm. 
So superstition is another kind of error. 

Fifth, the Pharisees committed a terrible error They were not h>7i' 
ocrites. They prayed sincerely, hut what they said was^ ^We thank thee 
that we are not as other men are'. 

Sixths to say that Jesus is not risen is false. Wittgenstein says that to 
believe in the resurrection is to belie^^e that Jesiis did not decompose in 
the grave like other teachers. The belief has an empirical element: god 
did not suffer his holy one to see corruption. 

These are simply some examples of uses of 'trutli' and 'falsity', and 
yet WittRcnsteinians arc said to deny the distinction. 

H 

/: The claltn Ihat a general distinction between the empirical and the 
religious is too sweeping is important. I was less worried about tiiat dis- 
nnctlon, than with bringing out the religious and ethical significance 
of notions like the Last Judgement which is lost if it is treated as a 
merely empirical event- But I agree with K that before we say that an 
event is this or tiiat, we must look to contexts to see the sense in which 
they might be taken together 

jB: You spoke of 'thcistic metaphysics^ What do you mean by that? Is it 

(o be dismissed and not taken seriously? 



D^.rmntps 147 



/: I didn't make much use of that term. I did refer to Hyman^s tendency 
to think that religious practices presuppose metaphysical beliefs. 
I argued against that. But there is little doubt that in Wittgenstein, 
'metaphj-'sics' is a term of abuse. Metaphysics is an attempt to solve 
problems that don't need solving because they are the product ot 
conceptual confusion. 

H: Isn't tliat because^ for Wittgenstein^ what is real in religion is found 
not in relation to reason, buL li^ relation to Chiist? 

C: I think we have to be carehit here- Firsts I would a^ce with K that at 
tlic time of the Tyactutiis or tlie Lecture on Ethics for that matter^ tlie rcli- 
gious expressions he wants to use are linked to the TnKUitis^ view of 
language, 1 agree that he is struggling to work his way out of that posi- 
tion in the Lt^ctures and Ciniversiitions without wholly succeeding. That 
is why he can't make sense of the expressions in the Tractatus and the 
Lecture svhile thinkings nevertheless, that they arc extremely important. 
The Importance of some of the rcmaiks, Lliercfore, sutvlves the philo- 
sophical position from which they were niade. So I don^t agree with 
K that tliey have little religious significance. For example, the view that 
when one comes lo helieve in God^ tlie world changes as a wliole is 
extremely important. 

In response to B Vd say that fitixe are times when Wittgenstein gives 
the impression that he Is the unconfused one^ whereas the metaphysi- 
cian is confused, as though he learnt nothing from the discussion of 
metaphysical theses. True^ he thinks these are confused^ but this is 
something which he comes to see through struggling with metaphysi- 
cal voices in the Ifwestigutioiij; which arc voices within himself. In the 
maiii he never dismissed metaphysical questions. He called them the 
deepest worries in philosopliy, alheit worries which we should strive to 
overcome. 



K: My main criticism is of the third pan of /'s paper 1 see no justification 
for his analo^^ between scepticism and sin. The source of the former is 
philosophical^ whereas the latter comes from the want of a proper rela- 
tionship with God. Coming to terms w^iLh scepticism doesn't lurn one's 
life around or bring salvation in the way in which receiving grace doe?. 

/: 1 wasn^t so much equating them as suggesting that there is an issue 

here to be addressed, both in relation to Christianity and Cavell's 
model of perfectionism. Cavell used the term 'recognition' and ivanted 
to explore what it or resistance to it involves. 



D^.rmntps 147 



/: I didn't make much use of that term. I did refer to Hyman^s tendency 
to think that religious practices presuppose metaphysical beliefs. 
I argued against that. But there is little doubt that in Wittgenstein, 
'metaphj-'sics' is a term of abuse. Metaphysics is an attempt to solve 
problems that don't need solving because they are the product ot 
conceptual confusion. 

H: Isn't tliat because^ for Wittgenstein^ what is real in religion is found 
not in relation to reason, buL li^ relation to Chiist? 

C: I think we have to be carehit here- Firsts I would a^ce with K that at 
tlic time of the Tyactutiis or tlie Lecture on Ethics for that matter^ tlie rcli- 
gious expressions he wants to use are linked to the TnKUitis^ view of 
language, 1 agree that he is struggling to work his way out of that posi- 
tion in the Lt^ctures and Ciniversiitions without wholly succeeding. That 
is why he can't make sense of the expressions in the Tractatus and the 
Lecture svhile thinkings nevertheless, that they arc extremely important. 
The Importance of some of the rcmaiks, Lliercfore, sutvlves the philo- 
sophical position from which they were niade. So I don^t agree with 
K that tliey have little religious significance. For example, the view that 
when one comes lo helieve in God^ tlie world changes as a wliole is 
extremely important. 

In response to B Vd say that fitixe are times when Wittgenstein gives 
the impression that he Is the unconfused one^ whereas the metaphysi- 
cian is confused, as though he learnt nothing from the discussion of 
metaphysical theses. True^ he thinks these are confused^ but this is 
something which he comes to see through struggling with metaphysi- 
cal voices in the Ifwestigutioiij; which arc voices within himself. In the 
maiii he never dismissed metaphysical questions. He called them the 
deepest worries in philosopliy, alheit worries which we should strive to 
overcome. 



K: My main criticism is of the third pan of /'s paper 1 see no justification 
for his analo^^ between scepticism and sin. The source of the former is 
philosophical^ whereas the latter comes from the want of a proper rela- 
tionship with God. Coming to terms w^iLh scepticism doesn't lurn one's 
life around or bring salvation in the way in which receiving grace doe?. 

/: 1 wasn^t so much equating them as suggesting that there is an issue 

here to be addressed, both in relation to Christianity and Cavell's 
model of perfectionism. Cavell used the term 'recognition' and ivanted 
to explore what it or resistance to it involves. 



i4S Flriitiwptiy of fif/JgTO?j m the 21 it Century 



C: Eutj ihcn^ what kind of rccogiiLtion arc wc talking about? I think 

ihc similarity comes from the fact that 'the spiriluar is wider Lhan 'the 
religious^ Wittgenstein said that wc must suffer in philosophy There is 
an analo;5y witli moral problems here because there is a question of the 
obstacle of the will involved - we wilt not give up certain w^ays of 
thinking. But, liaving said that, what wc are asked to recognize is wider 
than vvliat wc appropriate personally. For example^ compare St Francis 
saying that llie way flowers gave glory to God put him to shame, with 
Spandrel! in Huxley^s Point Cmmter Point slashing a field of flowers with 
his sLLck sa>an^, 'Dainn their insolence/ What is it to see the world in 
these ways? What sorl of disagreement exists between them? 

Philosophy itself is a spiritual determination to sec the w^orld as it is 
In all Its variety, but, for that very reason, it does not underwrite any 
perspective- Cavell seems to want to advocate specific perspectives. 1 do 
not think that he, or any other philosopher, can take that moral 
weight on himself. 

/: 1 agree with a great deal of that. I can see wtiy you say that taking on 
that moral weight cannot be part of a philosophical project. On the 
otlier hand, 1 was thinking of how ethical and spiritual concerns enter 
tliat philosophical discussion wliich is a love of msdom. After ail^ in 
some sense, you have to admit that youVe been lost. Why docs that 
repeat itself again and agaiii? Some conceptual confusions are very spe- 
cific, but tliey may still express the Impulse to violate criteria^ to speak 
outside language, and, therefore, to deny the human. 

E[ Aren't you referring to human problems^ not philosophical prob- 
lems? Oi are you saying that 'the human' includes 'the plillosophlcal'? 

/: Welt^ having rejected Malcolm's analogies^ Winch does not deny 
that philosophy can have a spiritual concern. He thought that 
Wittgenstein's investigations are suffused with It. So does a context 
emerge where there is a connection between a conception of pliilosophy 
and a conception of life? There is at least an issue here to be addrcssed. 

S: I was puzzled why K said that belief in the Resurrection involved an 
empirical element. Does he mean that you could settle the matter by 
checking whether the tomb was empty? Suppose someone said that 
Hitler had walked uui of an empty tomb, ^o what? What religious 
significance would it have? 

Pi I think we need to recognize that language games overlap in this 
context. There is no sharp distinction between the empirical and the 

spitituaL 



K: Exactly. Tlio Giiiipirical is the condition of ihc sptritual. If Christ is 
not risen, then, indeed^ our f^iUh Ls ii^ vain. 

A\ If one is a religious believer one musl aslc what sort of person would 
liave brought about such an event, just as one asks what sort of person 
would liavc committed a crime, [f you say there can^t be any such thing 
as a resurrection you1l need a lot of evidence to show this. But if you 
liave a belief that it is probable that there is a God^ then you must ask 
wlietlier It is reasonable and probable lliat he would do such a thing. 

7^ Wittgenstein says tliat religious believers walk a tightrope with 
beliefs of this kind. II: you ovcr-emphasize some aspect you fall off, but 
people do manage to walk tlie tightrope. 

Ct One way of falling off the tiglitiope is to say as K does that the 
resurrection is the empirical condiMon of religious faith- That cannot 
possibly be right because 'resurrection' is itself a religious notion. 

K: But for you ^raised" simply means '"exalted'. You believe the bones of 

Jesus arc somew^hcre in Palestine. 

— - ^-|-.-■ -»-,- 

C: You referred to Wittgenstein endorsing your view. I don't tliiiik ho 

does. I believe there Is a change of direction in the passage you 
referred. He says, at firsts that he plays with the thought that to be 
saved he needs Jesus not lo have decomposed in the grave like any 
other teacher. Now, 1 have no idea where the bones of Jesus are, but It 
docs nol take love to believe that they are not in Palestine. And when 
Wittgenstein turns away from the thought tbal he was playing witli^ 
that is what he says - that it takes love to believe that the crucified one 
lias been raised on high, exalted to the right liand of God tire Father 
Now If you think this invites the empirical question, 'How high was he 
raised?' that is your problem. Are you going to ask the same empirical 
question of the Ascension? These are rcUgious terms and must be 
understood as sueh. 

F: Christianity is an historical religion - things hapfx^n at a certain 
time. liut it doesn't follow that svhat happened is itself lo be deter- 
mined historically. The WTiters of the Gospels were not writing an his- 
torical report, but proclaiming Good News. C is right, the Resurrection 
is. part of that Good News. It's not as though a video camera couid 
have picked it up. They arc not CNN rcporters- 

D: How do you know a video camera could not have picked it up? 
F: Tliat wasn't my claim - it couldn't. 



150 Flrihiwphy ofReiistou m the Zlst Century 



El K^ you were rcfcmng to 1 Corinlhiaiis 15. There, for Paul, without a 
doubt^ resurrection and exaltation come Lo the same thing. 

A: That's a disputable view; we'd need Lo look al the texts. 

K: It Is certainly disputable. Paul refers uncqutvocally to the post- 
resurreclion appearances^ on wl:tich the faith of the believers depends. 

E: And he says that he Is passing on what lie, too, has received. 

C: In other words, the sense in which Jesus appeared to him is the 
5ame sense as thai in which he appeared to others. 

D: I think that if you ask most Christians whether they think that they 
would deny it. 

C: But w^hat makes you think you can do jrfitlosophy in that way? If 1 
knocked on a door in Claremont and asked the lady of the house what 
she meant by 'thinkings would i take her answer to settle the matter? 
One cannot do philosophy by Gallup polk 

D: Why not? Wittgensteinians always claim to tell us what wc really 
mean. Why not ask Christians what they do mean? If the majority says 
they mean such-and-such, that settles the matter. You can do this kind 
of philosophy by Gallup poll. 

C: No you can^t, because when reference is made to what people mean, 
the reference is to the role the w^ords play in their liveSn not to the 
account they would give if asked. Notoiiouslyn In giving that account 
our own words can lead us astray. That is why Wittgenstein said that 
though a picture, including a religious picture, is in the foreground, its 
actual application may be in the background. The matter can only be 
resolved, if at all^ through discussion with one's interlocutor It cannot 
be settled by Gallup polk 



Part IV 



Postmodernism 



10 

Messianic Postmodernism 

Joluj D. Capitto 



The word 'postmodernism' has come lo mean many things. So before 

addressing the principal objections diat have been made against it^ 
particularly as regards its usefulness as a framework for a pliaJoscjpiiy of 
rehgion, we would do well lo specify the sense in which we are using 
this term. Very broadly conceived^ I would argue that poslmodcjrnism 
is a philosophy of difference', that it emphasizes the productive role of 
difference, as opposed to the 'modern' or Enlightenment predilection 
for universality, commonalit)'^ consensus, and wliat modernists {rather 
presumptuously) call 'rationality'. Speaking very broadly still, 1 would 
say that, for our purposes here, there are (at least) two different vari- 
eties of this philosophy of diffcrcncCj depending on wliJch of its two 
nineteenth-century predecessors - Nietzsche or Ktcrkcigaard - one 
favours. Tliesc 1 will call^ only slightly tongue in clicckj 'Dionysian' 
and 'messianic' postmodernism. 

[t is the thesis of the present essay that most of the objections that 
are made aj^ainst postmodernism have in mind tlic EMonysian veRion^ 
but that they fall wide of the mark o! \hc messianic version, about 
which the critics of postmodernism often seem badly informed. The 
line of objections that are raised against postmodcrnisLs bear a family 
resemblance: relativism^ sub|cctiv:sm, scepticism, anarcltism, antinomi- 
antsm, anti-institutionaltsm, nihilism and despair- In my view^ this line 
of complatnc takes its lead from the highly Nictzscheanizcd face of tlie 
first version of postmodernism, but it docs not come to grips with the 
Kicrtccgaardian {and Lcvinasian) face of the second version. Clearly, 
were all or most of these objections valid^ postmodernism would not be 
of much help to the philosophy of religion, or to anything else for that 
matter, and it would be rightly denounced as mimical to God and reli- 
gion. Although I will argue that when these complaints arc legitimate^ 



153 



154 Flrihiwptiy ofRi^H^ou m the 21 it Century 

they hold of its Dionysian version^ I would insist that a more nuanced 
understanding of this version also reveals very interesting possibiliLics 
foT religious reflection. The danger of the piescnt 'good cop^^ad cop^ 
strategy is that it tends to sell the Xietzschean version shortj to throw 
it to the wolves of postmodern ism's critles, and to let it take a hit for 
the rest of us. But be that as h may, this string of objections against 
postmodernism is^ as regards the second or messianic version, false 
oil its face and very likely belra^^ the critic's unfamiharlty with its reli- 
gious and even bibttcal provenance- 



Dionysian postmodern istn 

Tlie Nietzschean version of postmodernism has grabbed most of the 

headlines and has dominated its popular reception. In this version of ihe 
philosophy of difference {heteros)^ difference has the sense of dh'eraitas^ 
the variety of forms. Here the emphasis Is placed upon the affirmation of 
multiplicity, a multiplication of fomiSn a pol^^iorphic or 'heteromorphic' 
pluralism of many different kinds. This goes hand iii hand with a love 
of noveltyj of the Invention of as many new kinds as possible- Philo- 
sophically this view draws upon Nietzsche's 'perspectLvalism', that is, 
his critique of 'truth^ and the 'ascetic ideal'. Nietzsche was critical of the 
classical metaphysical ideal that there is a firm centre which holdSj a 
firm and immutable foundation or principle, to which all lovers of the 
true or the good, of science or ethics, must rigorously (^ascelically^l 
hold - whether one takes that principle to be Godn the laws of physics, 
or even the laws of grammar. Indeed^ wlien Xietzsche said that 'God is 
d^ad\ he meant this entire metaphysical order, any notiori of an 
absolute centre or foundation. That explains wiiy he said we would not 
be rid of belief in God until we had dispelled our belief in grammar, 
our belief that wliat arc for him the 'fictions' - or conventions - of 
.-indo-European grammar somehow give voice to the very order of 
bein^ (the grammatical subject arousing faith in the personal self^ and 
so forth), fn the place of this absolutism^ Nietzsche put his notion of 
perspectives, that every belief^ including the propositions of physics, is 
an interpretation. 

For XietzscliCn the perspectives issue from the play of forces asserting 
themselves, each with greater or lesser strength, each expressing its 
own immanent life force to a greater ot lesser extent. Our own 'beliefs^ 
are the perspectives we cognitive beings impose on things to promote 
tlie flourishing of our ow^n life, rather the way the trees in the forest 
istruggle for light. When Nietzsche complained, 'if there were a God, 



John D. Capiito 135 



whzLt would Ihcrc be kft for us to create?^ he pressed the view thai the 

n:iaxiniization of the invention of the perspectives required the disnian- 
tling of the idea of a siimmum bommf or primmn ens in which every such 
possihility would be already realized. For Nietzsche no belief or idea 
enjoyed eternal or timeless validity; every such idea is invented - histor- 
ically constituted - to promote the needs of life, fndecd, one is tempted 
to argue that for Nietzsche such ideas are biologically constituted^ so 
long as one does not forget that biology toO' is another perspective and 
ought not to be turned into another ascetic ideal, lliat is, a rigorous, 
absolutely true^ non-pcrspc clival science lo which cvciytliiiig caii be 
systematically reduced. Ever)ihin^ is surface, surface is what is deep; 
the distinction between depth and surface^ the true world and apparent, 
being and appearing, comes undone. God is dead. 

The most prominent 'Xietzschean' postmodernists arc Gillcs Delcuze 
and Michel Foucault and nowadays, after their death, Jean Baudrillard, 
ivho uses Nietzschean presuppositions In a 'postmodern' theory of 
^images'. Oaudrillard represents a very importantn more broadly 'cultural' 
dimension of postniodernisraj one which forces us to distinguish it from 
a more technical philosophical position called post-slrjcturalism. In 
Baudrillard^ postmodernism is the articulation of the culture of the 
world-Vh-ide web and 'virtual realit)^ ^po^ which we have all entered^ 
where the distinction between image and reality, surface and depths 
dissolves- As his recent CD-Rom. The Ri^nk Las Vegas, NV, illustrates 
very well^ this is the 'poslmodefn' world that today interests radical 
theologian Vlark C. Taylor.^ Feminist theologians like Sharon Welch 
and Rebecca Chopp have made interesting use of Foucauldian inspired 
'genealogical' anal}'scs to criticize the historically constituted constena- 
tions of power and sexuality that have been used to oppress women 
and minorities^ inside the church and without. In still another direc- 
tion^ Bataille had taken up Nietzsche's notion of tlie overflowing of the 
will to powder to formulate a theory of an expenditure without return 
as the essence of the religious act. 

On the whole, this version of postmodernism has been greeted w^ith 
hostility by a wide variety of thinkers oii both the left and the right, by 
scientists and humanists alike. The right wing tends to think Nietzsche 
is the devil himself^ having utterly relativized^ God-Motherhood-and- 
Apple-Piety. But then again so does the ^old' Olberal, modernist) left^ 
which has no interest in religion at all, as witness pJiysicist Alan Sokal^ 
who wants to restore the left to its p re-Nietzsche an senses^ has made a 
reputation for himself denouncing the 'cultural studies' movement, 
made up of postmodernists of the Dionysian stripe, wlio on his view 



156 Flrihiwphy ofRi^H^ou Ui the 21 it Century 

aK ill-tnforniGd charlatans attempting to rclaEivizG the results of mathc- 
matical physics while knowing UllIc niaLhcmalics and less physics. Even 
Richard Rorty^ who thinks that Nietzsche is gcKxl for use on weekends 
when we arc invcnling our private selves^ is hij^hly critical of letting 
Nietzsche into the workaday public sphere^ with Ihe confusion besetting 
the new left, as he argues in liis recent Adiicviti^ onr Cotmtfy? Philoso- 
phical theologians like Brian Ingraffia have roundly criticized Nietzsche 
for having a defective understanding of Christianity and on this basis 
have denounced any attompt to mix Christianity and postmod<^rnisni.-* 
That is, 1 think, an ovcrreaetionj bul it is an understandable reaction 
that this version of postmodernist thinking tends to bring down upon 
itself- At its best, Nietzscheanized postmodernism has opened up 
important genealogical investigations into the historical constitution 
of power clusters that can have emancipatory effects for the oppressed, 
and have paved the way for the new or what Allan B!oom grumpily 
called Che 'Nietzscheanized left\ a pnliUcal result that would, needless 
to say, have profoundly saddened Nietzsche himself who was deeply 
antipathetic to modern democratic movements and who deeply regretted 
the passing of the cmcien regm:e in France. At its worst, postmodernists 
often give us the impression that they have utterly jettisoned any stan- 
dard of reason^ intelligibility or argumentation; they give everyone the 
distinct impression that 'anything goes' just l>ccause their texts are 
written precisely as if anything does indeed go They make themselves 
easy targets for people like Sokal who have neither the time, the train- 
ing, nor the taste for trying to decode and decipher the excesses of 
tlicir jargon. They write for an inside group of 'po-mo' academics^ bolt- 
ing from one conference on postmodernism to the ncxt^ presenting 
the worst but most public face of this movement. 

Messianic Postmodernism 



liut 'postmodernism'' is capable of assuming a second and quite different 
form, one whose nineteenth-century predecessor is not Nietzsche but 
Kierkegaard. Here the notion of 'difference' lakes on a significantly differ- 
ent sense, where it means not divensltas, or heteromorphic diversity, but 
rather tilteritus, the alteriLy of the 'other one', that one 'over there'- In the 
second vers;ion, difference demands tr'imsct'fideijce, the movement fronn 
the 'same^ to the ^other^^ a movement first aruiounced in philosophy by 
Plato, who said that the Good is ^pikeiiias tes ottsias, beyond being, at the 
end of a steep ascent^ and in religion by the transcendence of tlie Most 



JoimU. Capiito 157 

Highn the Holy One of Second Tsaiah^ Who said that His ways aic not 
our ways. Here difrcrcncc means the One Who Is 'wholly other' {tout 
autre), to use the expression that Levinas borrows from Vladimir 
YankelevilchH wlio was wriliiig about the One in Plotinus^ although thai 
expression is also found in Kierkegaard. 

By the wholly other these thinkers inean the 'paradox^ - by which they 
do not mean not some simple logical contradiction [jc and -;f) - of a con- 
cept of sometlilng inconceivable^ a concept whose verj' meaning or con- 
ceptual function is to indicate something beyond, something we cannot 
conceive and comprehend^ not just because of present liniitatlons but 
always and in principle. A classteal example of this is the Anselmian Godn 
hi ijiio imijo!' neqait cogiUiti, the concept of what we cannot conceive^ of 
something so surpassingly great that It is always and in principle better 
than anything we can conceive. Such concepts have a principle of self- 
surpassal built right into them. So^ too, the Cartesian notion in the 
Third Meditation of an idea of something of which 1 can have no Idea, 
an idea that has been implanted in me that 1 cannot understand, yiz., 
of an infinite God. The Svholly othci' Is always like thai. It is not going 
to turn out upon further investigation to be an instance of a type of 
which I already have an idea, so that I am already schematically familiar 
with it. It has an un reach ability, an un attainability - an alterit\^ - built 
into it, like a shore for which 1 set out but never reach. I am in relation 
with it, heading for it, but the 'wholly other' is also always withdrawing 
frpni this relaliotiH ^f> that^ lii principle, 1 never get there. The paradox 
is encapsulated nicely in Levinas's phrase, 'a relation in which the 
tersiis absolve themselves from the relation^ remain absolute within tlie 
relation' p^ or in Blanchot's French qulp^ Je'pas mf-deliif taking the 'step 
ipiis) beyond', which is also prohibited, the 'no-bcyond' (le 'pus. mi-iielii'), 
the step not beyond, the step I ara always taking but not quite making- 
There Is both a relation and a breakdown of the relation, like a desire 
to have what cannot be had, or to know what cannot be known- So if 
in the Dionj^ian version of postmodern difference, ^infinite' tended to 
mean the unregulatable and uncontrollable play of differences spread- 
ing across an infinite iiorizontal surface^ 'rliizomatically'^ as Dcleuze 
would say fwhich means like crab grass)^ in this second version, infi- 
nite difference has the sense of unreachable depths or heights, like the 
Ancient of Days or the Most High in the Tanakh. 

If tiiie Dionysian version of difference takes the form of a certain 
Iteteromorphism', this second version, which I am calling ^messianic', 
is best tliought of as a certain ^hcteronomism""^ where everything turns 



i5S Flriitiwphy ofReiistou m the 21 it Century 



oil the iaw of the other, on the disruption visited upon the 'same^ by the 
'othcr'j which Is ihc language Levinas uses, adapted from Plato's Sophist 
and Piirmetiuies, to express a very biblical notion. In tlii5 version, what 
matters is the 'responsibihty' that 1 incur wlien the other overtakes me, 
taking me tay a kind of deep surprise, one that is older than 1 can say, 
prefi;^fcd in the very ^tmcture of creatio ex ffihUo, in which, in Lcvinas^s 
beautiful phrase, tlie creature answers lo a call that it never heard. The 
hetcronomic version is structured around llie notion of a call in which 
the other lays claim to me, has always and aEready laid claim to me. Its 
model and protot)'"pe is no one less than father Abraham himself, who, 
called forth from the land of his fathers never to ro home again, and 
called upon to sacrifice the seed of the very future he was promised 
for this uprooting, could only say 'fiineiu^ 'me ^mci^ see me here, 
here 1 am. In the Dionysian version of postmodernism, modernities 
autonomous subject is dispersed and disseminated into a Dionysian plu- 
raltty of many selves, each one of which Is historically, even grammati- 
cally constituted- In the heteronomlc version, the modern autonomous 
subject is taken from behind^ overtaken, by a call which it never heard, 
by a command of which it is not the author^ by a past that was never 
present, and reduced - led back' - to a levet of deeper subjection and 
accusation, radically sinjjularizcd by an Inescapable, irrecusable responsi- 
bility. The Cartesian l"" of modernity becomes a biblical ^me^ in the 
accusative, accused by the call which claims it. 'Abraham!^ 'See me hereJ^ 
Thus far from being the nemesis of religion and ethical rcsponsibtlilyp 
which is the complaint directed al its Dionysian cousin, the figures of 
this postmodern ism, where the term 'postmodern^ marks a m^^ditation 
^ 0n 'alterity', are distinctly ethlealn biblical and, as I will show, messianic. 
Indeed, this discourse has been described by Derrlda as 'a non-dogmatic 
doublet of dogma. -.a thhikm^ th^l '^repeats'' the possibility of religion 
without religion""- This 'thinking', Derrida says, is 'developed witlrout 
reference to reh^ion as institutional dogma,' and concerns 'the essence 
of the religious that doesn^l amount to an article of faith'^ representing 
a body of 'discourses that seek In our day to be religious.-. witlioul 
putting forth theses or thedogems that would by their very structure 
teach something corresponding to the dogmas of a given religion'.^ 

Although Derrida is speaking of Kierkegaard and Lcvinas,^ among 
others, I have argued elsewhere and at some length that this 'religion 
without religion' also befits Derrida himselfj particularly as regards the 
works that have appeared since 19K07 This claim is anathema both 
to secularizing deconstructionists, who on the question of religion 
repeat deeply modernist critiques of religion A^'ith perfect loyalty, and 



Jo)mD. Capiito 159 



to religious thinkers^ who^ like Brian Ingraffia^ mislakenly identify 
dGconstruction as a form of Dioiiysian rather than of messianic post- 
modernism. But to the surprise and diagrin of many, Derrida, it turns 
outp has religion, lA'hat he calls 'my religion^ and U can he i^ored only 
at the cost of systematically misreading his work. Indeed, time and time 
again the most outrageous and, one is Ecmpted to say, the most irrespoit- 
siblc misrepresentations of his work appear regularly in prints grotesque 
distortions of a thinker whose principal interest these days lies in such 
notions as the messianic, hospitality, friendship, testimony and forgive- 
ness. That is due to the fact that in Dcrrida there are important veins of 
both versions of postmodernisms, very roughly approximating his ear- 
lier and later writings, and that too many conimentators go by second- 
liand accounts of the earlier work. Indeed, getting one's reading of 
Derrida right is a good case study in being able Co identify these different 
tendencies in postmodernism and the way they interact. 

The prhiclpal document In w^hlch the religious, or as we shall shortly 
sec, the messianic clement in Dcrrida's work most clearly emerges is 
his Ciu'Offfcssum, an autobiographical book woven together with 
St Augustine's Confe5:?i(}nSf wliieh appeared in 1990, on the dual occa- 
sion of reaching his fiftieth year and of the death of his mother.^ Here 
Derrida recounts his upbringing as an Algerian Jew and 3. pied noiif as an 
Arab/Jew who speaks 'Christian Latin French' in the land w^here Augus- 
tine was born (he was raised on the rue Sriihit Au^iistin). Circonfesj^ioa, 
tlie confessions of a cifcumcised Augustine, a Jewish Augustine^ is an 
attempt, he says, to leave nothings if possiblCj in the dark of w^hat 
related me to Judaism^ alliance broken in every respect^ Of this 
alliance, 'without continuity but without break', he says 'that's what 
my teaders won't have known about me', 'like my religion about 
wliich nobody understands anything', and the result Is tliat he is ^rcad 
less and less well over almost tw'cnty years"". Jacques is also the fiiius 
istiimni liicrynhinmi whose mother George tte/\Ionica, now dying oh 
the shores of the other side of the Mediterranean In Nice/Ostian w^ept 
and w^orrlcd over whether Jacques still believed in God, never darliig to 
ask Jacques himselfn 'but she must have known that the constancy of 
God in my life is called by other namcs\ even though he 'rightly passes 
for an atheisf QD, pp. 154-5). 

Nothing better embodies and Illustrates the convergence of religion 
and postmodernism than tlie emergence of the 'religion/ of Jacques 
Derrida, his 'religion without je-ligion', and nothing more effectively 
lays to rest the misguided idea that religion is irrelevant to ^deconstruc- 
tion' - tlie version of postmodernism 1 ayHI focus on now - and that 



160 Flrihiwphy of fif/JgTO?j m the 21 it Century 



deconstruction is irrelevant to religious reflection. Tlie central mterest 
of the debate about Derrida and fcll^lon up to now has been the ques- 
tion of negative thcology_ Tt Is certainly true that Derrida loves negative 
the ology^ because it consti tutcs a paradoxical di scou rsc organized 
around a self-effacing name - the name of God - a name that is betrayed 
as soon as it is uttered. Nothing pleases Deriida more than Meistcr 
Eckhart's beautiful and famous prayer^ 1 pray God to rid me of God.^ 
Derrida stands in toving awe of the resources of negative theolo^v; of 
its attempt to 'go where you cannot go\ as the mystical [>oet Angekis 
Silesius wrote. Negative theology is for him an ancient archive of the 
deepest attempts that have been made to learn how to avoid speaking, 
to speak ivilhout speakings how not to speak. Comineut }ie puj; parier? 
But he differs fundamentally with negative theology, which he regards, 
in one of its voices at least, as inevitably 'hypcrousiological'. However 
much it protests tliat it does not know, negative theology^ always knows 
In a certain way just what It does not know; and always manages to 
affirm something al! the more essentially by way of its negations, Nega- 
tive theolog); Derrida says^ always knows where to direct its prayers."^ 

Derrida is more interested in its 'other' voices the darkest night of its 
soul, when it truly does not know for what it prays and w^eeps. Qttiil 
ergo atiio cum dcii}}f memu timo?, St Augustine WTites. Derrida says that 
he has been asking this question all his life: wliat do 1 love when I love 
my God? It is not a question of wlicthcr he toves God - who would be 
.^o cold of heart to deny that? - but of what he loves when he loves his 
God. He has, I>errida says, all his life lon^ been 'hoping sighing dream- 
ing^ of something tmit iiutre, something raaivellous to comc^ something 
'undcconstnjctible' which is the heart and soul^ the prayers and tears, 
the impulse and the point of de construction. Deconstruction, to the 
consternation of its Nietzscheanising, secularizing admirers^ and to the 
no lesser consternation of its conservative religious allies, turns out 
to be a rchglon of the tout autre, a religious affirmation of w^hat is to 
coine, hoping and sigliing, dreaming and praying for the coming of 
the whollv other 

But this religion is to be understood not in terms of i:iegative theology 
but in morejewishj ^messianic' Leims. The present preoccupation with 
deconstruction and negative theology fails to see that deconstruction is 
more prophetic than mystical, more preoccupied with messianic peace 
and justice than mystical union, more Je wash than Christian-Platonic. 
Deconstruction, Derrida says, is best conceived as the affirmation of 
the i4mieconstruct:b{t\ which lie also describes as the affirmation of