Skip to main content

Full text of "Mind"

See other formats


BINDING  LIST  NO  V  1  5  1922 


, 


MIND 


A    QUARTERLY    REVIEW 

OF 

PSYCHOLOGY    AND    PHILOSOPHY. 


ABERDEEN:  THE  UNIVERSITY  PRESS 


MIND 


A     QUARTERLY     REVIEW 


OF 


PSYCHOLOGY     AND     PHILOSOPHY. 


EDITED    BY 


G.  E.  MOORE, 


WITH  THE  CO-OPERATION  OF  PROFESSOR  PR1NGLE-PATTISON,  PROFESSOR 
C.  D.  BROAD,  AND  F.  C.  BARTLETT,  M.A. 


NEW    SERIES. 


VOL.  XXXI.-I922. 


LONDON: 

MACMILLAN     &     CO.,     LIMITED, 

ST.    MARTIN'S    STREET,   W.C. 

1922. 


CONTENTS  OF  VOLUME  XXXI. 


(NEW  SERIES.) 
ARTICLES. 

PAGE 

AVELING,  F. — Is  the  Conception  of  the  Unconscious  of  Value  in  Psycho- 
logy?    (Symposium] 423 

CARE,  H.  WILDON. — Einstein's  Theory  and  Philosophy  ....  169 
V^COLLINGWOOD,  B.  G. — Are  History  and  Science  different  kinds  of  Know-  s" 

ledge?     (Symposium) 443 

EDGEWORTH,  F.  Y. — The  Philosophy  of  Chance 257 

FAWCETT,  D. — Imaginism  and  the  World-Process 154 

FIELD,  G.  C. — The  Psychological  Accompaniments  of  Instinctive  Action  129 
„          „    — Is  the  Conception  of  the  Unconscious  of  Value  in  Psycho- 
logy?    (Symposium) 413 

GREGORY,  J.  C. — Visual  Images,  Words,  and  Dreams     ....  321 
HICKS,  G.  DAWES. — The  Philosophical  Researches  of  Meinoug  (I.)  -        -  1- 
LAIRD,  J. — Is  the  Conception  of  the  Unconscious  of  Value  in  Psycho- 
logy?    (Symposium) 433 

LUTOSLAWSKI,  W. — A  Theory  of  Personality 53 

RANDLE,  H.  N. — Sense-data  and  Sensible  Appearances  in  Size-Distance 

Perception        -                           284 

•  SCHILLER,  F.  C.  S.  — An  Idealist  in  Extremis  -        -                 ...  144 
^          ,,                ,,      — Are  History  and  Science  different  kinds  of  Know- 
ledge ?     (Symposium) -  459 

SELLARS,  R.  WOOD. — Concerning  "  Transcendence  "  and  "  Bifurcation  "  31 

STOUT,  G.  F.— Prof.  Alexander's  Theory  of  Sense  Perception  -        -        -  385 

j^ STRONG,  C.  A.— Mr.  Russell's  Theory  of  the  External  World  307 
^/TAYLOR,  A.  E. — Are  History  and  Science  different  kinds  of  Knowledge  ? 

(Symposium) 451 

TEMPLE,  W.,  Bishop  of  Manchester. — Symbolism  as  a   Metaphysical 

Principle 467 

TURNER,   J.   E.— Dr.   Wildon  Carr  and  Lord  Haldane  on   Scientific 

Relativity 40 


DISCUSSIONS. 

V^  AINSCOUGH,  R. — Some  Remarks  on  Relativity 489 

BOSANQUET,  B.—"  This  or  Nothing  " 178 

„  —A  Word  about  Coherence  -  335 

s  GREENWOOD,  T. — Einstein  and  Idealism  -  -  205 

HIGHT,  G.  A.— Plato  and  the  Poets  -  -  -  -  195 

MACKENZIE,  J.  S. — Universal s  and  Orders 189 

RUSSELL,  B. — Physics  and  Perception  -  -  ....  473 

SCHILLER,  F.  C.  S.— The  Meaning  of  "  Self  "  185 


VI  CONTENTS. 

PAGE 

STRONG,  C.  A. — The  Meaning  of  "  Meaning  "  69 

x        „           „    —Rejoinder 486 

/  TURNER,  J.  E. — Relativity,  Scientific  and  Philosophical         -         -         -  337 
/  WRINCH,  D. — On  certain   Methodological    Aspects  of  the   Theory  of 

Relativity 200 

CRITICAL  NOTICES. 

JOHNSON,  W.  E.— Logic :   Part  II.  (C.  D.  Broad) 496 

JONES,  Sir  H.—  A  Faith  that  Enquires  (J.  S.  Mackenzie)        -        -        -  343 

KEYNES,  J.  M. — A  Treatise  on  Probability  (C.  D.  Broad)        ...  72 

MEYERSON,  E. — De  V Explication  dans  les  Sciences  (L.  Russell)      -        -  510 

RUSSELL,  B. — The  Analysis  of  Mind  (A.  Dorward)  85 

NEW  BOOKS. 

ALEXANDER,  S. — Spinoza  and  Time  (H.  F.  Hallett)        ....  221 

Aristotelian  Society,  Proceedings  of  the,  1920-21  (H.  Barker)  -        -        -  223 

BAILLIE,  J.  B. — Studies  in  Human  Nature  (L.  Russell)  -        ...  98 
BENGOECHEA,  J.  Z. — Contribucion  del  Lenguaje  a  la  Filosofia  de  ios 

Valores  (F.  C.  S.  Schiller) 239 

BEVAN,  E. — Hellenism  and  Christianity  (A.  E.  Taylor)  ....  352 

BLONDEL,  M.— L'Azione  (H.  Wildon  Carr) 239 

BOAS,  G.—An  Analysis  of  Certain  Theories  of  Truth  (F.  C.  S.  Schiller)  362 
BOURGUES,  L.,  and  A.  DENEREAZ. — La  Musique  et  la  Vie  Interieure 

(H.  J.  Watt) 237 

BRETT,  G.  &.—A  History  of  Psychology,  Vols.  II.  and  III.  (J.  L.  M.)     -  525 
BRIFFAULT,  R.—The  Making  of  Humanity  (C.  C.  J.  W.)                 -        -  225 
BROWN,  W.,  and  G.  H.  THOMSON. — The  Essentials  of  Mental  Measure- 
ment (C.  W.  Valentine) 236 

CARLINI,  A.~La  Vita  dello  Spirito  (H.  Wildon  Carr)  239 
GLAPAREDK,  E. — Psychologic  de  V Enfant  et  Pedagogic  Experimental 

(F.  G.  B.)                                                                                          -        -  109 
COHEN,  H. — Die  Religion der  Vernunft  aus  denQuellen  des  Judenthums 

(H.  R.  Mackintosh) 227 

DECOSTER,  P.— Le  Regne  de  la  Pensee  (L.  Russell)        ....  366 
DENEREA-Z,  A.,  and  L.  BOURGUES. — La  Musique  et  la  Vie  Interieure 

(H.  J.  Watt) 237 

FIELD,  G.  C.— Moral  Theory  (J.  Laird) 217 

FLUGEL,  J.  G.—The  Psycho-analytical  Study  of  the  Family  ( W.  Whately 

Smith) 370 

GALLI,  E. — Alle  Radici  della  Morale  (B.  Bosanquet)      ....  220 
„       ,,—Nel  Dominio  dell' "lo  "   (            „,)---        -  220 
J}       ,,—Nel  Mondo  dello  Spirito  (            ,,          )  220 
GARNETT,  J.  C.  M. — Education  and  World  Citizenship  (C.  W.  Valen- 
tine) 210 
GINSBERG,  M.— The  Psychology  of  Society  (G.  C.  Field)  368 
HEATH,  A.  G.— The  Moral  and  Social  Significance  of  the  Conception  of 

Personality  (R.  F.  A.  H.) 100 

HIRST,  E.  Vf.—Self  and  Neighbour  (H.  J.  W.  H.)          ....  359 

HOBHOUSE,  L.  T.—The  Elements  of  Social  Justice  (P.  V.  M.  Benecke)  -  372 
HOFFDING,  H. — Bemerkungen  iiber  den  Platonischen  Dialog  Parmenides 

(A.  E.  Taylor)  > 373 

HOLLING WORTH,  H.  L. — The  Psychology  of  Functional  Neuroses  (W. 

Whately  Smith)       ...  107 

HOWLEY,  J. — Psychology  and  Mystical  Experience  (J.  W.  Scott)    -        -  105 

JOAD,  C.  E.  M. — Common-Sense  Ethics  (J.  Laird) 217 

JONES,  Sir  H.,  and  J.  H.  MUIRHEAD. — The  Life  and  Philosophy  of  Ed- 
ward Caird  (B.  Bosanquet) "  350 


CONTENTS.  Vll 

PAGE 

KEITH,  A.  B. — Indian  Logic  and  Atomism  (S.  N.  Dasgupta)  -        -        -  231 
LAMPKBCHT,  S.  P. — T}ie  Moral  and  Political  Philosophy  of  John  Locke 

(J.  G.) Ill 

LANGFELD,  H.  S.— The  Aesthetic  Attitude  (C.  W.  Valentine)  -  -  371 
LEON,  X.—Fichte  et  son  Temps,  Vol.  I.  (J.  E.  McTaggart)  363 
LEVF,  A.— La  Filosofia  di  Giorgio  Berkeley  (A.  E.  T.)  -  -  375 
MATTHEWS,  W.  R. — Studies  in  Christian  Philosophy  (F.  R.  Tennant)  -  229 
MENTRE,  F.—Especes  et  Varietes  d' Intelligences  (B.  Bosanquet)  -  -  234 
MORE,  P.  E.— The  Religion  of  Plato  (A.  E.  Taylor)  518 
MUIRHEAD,  J.  H.,  and  Sir  H.  JONES. — The  Life  and  Philosophy  of  Ed- 
ward Caird  (B.  Bosanquetj -  350 

MULLER-FREIENFELS,  R. — Persb'nlichkeit  und  Weltanschauung  (F.  C.  S. 

Schiller) 110 

POYNTING,  J.  H. —  Collected  Scientific  Papers  (G.  Dawes  Hicks)     -         -  102 

READ,  C.  S. — Military  Psychiatry  in  Peace  and  War  (W.  L.  M.)  -        -  109 

RENSI,  G. — Lineamenti  di  Filosofia  Scettica  (F.  C.  S.  Schiller)      -        -  367 

REYBURN,  H.  A.— The  Ethical  Theory  of  Hegel  (J.  S.  Mackenzie)          -  356 

ROYCE,  J. — Fugitive  Essays  (J.  Laird)  -                  Ill 

RUIN,  H.—Erlebnis  und  Wissen  (F.  C.  S.  Schiller)  240 

SCHOLZ,  H. — Die  Religions2)hilosophie  des  Als  Ob  (F.  C.  S.  Schiller)     -  354 

SELLARS,  R.  W  .—Evolutionary  Naturalism  (H.  F.  Hallett)  360 

SEMON,  R.—The  Mneme  (A.  D.  R.) 233 

SORLEY,  W.  R.— A  History  of  English  Philosophy  (A.  E.  Taylor)           -  208 

STAGE,  W.  T.—A  Critical  History  of  Greek  Philosophy  (A.  E.  Taylor)    -  238 
STERN,   W.—Die    Differentielle    Psychologie    in    ihren    methodischen 

Grundlagen  (F.  C.  B.)      -                          374 

THOMAS,  E.  E.— Lome's  Theory  of  Reality  (J.  Laird)                        -        -  365 
THOMSON,  G.  H.,  and  W.  BROWN.—  The  Essentials  of  Mental  Measure- 
ment (C.  W.  Valentine) -        -        -  236 

URQUHART,  W.  S. — Pantheism  and  the  Value  of  Life  (S.  N.  Dasgupta)  230 

VARENDONCK,  J. — The  Psychology  of  Day-dreams  (T.  H.  Pear)       -        -  213 

WINDBLBAND,  W. — An  Introduction  to  Philosophy  (H.  Barker)      -        -  521 


PHILOSOPHICAL  PERIODICALS. 

British  Journal  of  Psychology  (x.,  4,  July,  1920;  xi.,  1,  Oct.,  1920)        -  115 

,,            ,,             „              (xi.,  2  and  3,  Jan.  and  April,  1921)  -         -  243 

,,             „            ,,              (xii.,  1,  June,  1921) 378 

„             „              (xii.,  2,  Oct.,  1921) 530 

International  Journal  of  Ethics  (xxxi.,  Oct.,  1920-July,  1921)         -        -  117 

„            ,,            (xxxii.,  1,  Oct.,  1921)  252 

(     „       2,  Jan.,  1922)    ....  535 

Journal  of  Philosophy  (xviii.  (1921),  11-26) 244 

(xix.  (1922),  1-2) 247 

(  „  (1922),  3-5) 379 

(  „  (1922),  6-9) 534 

Logos  (iv.,  2-3,  April-Sept.,  1921) 248 

„      (iv.,  4,  Oct.-Dec.,  1921) 531 

Revue  Ne'o-Scolastique  de  Philosophic  (xxiii.,  91  and  92,  Aug.  and  Nov., 

1921) 249 

(xxiv.,  93,  Feb.,  1922)  ...  534 

Revue  de  Philosophic  (Jan. -Aug.,  1921) 119 

(Sept.-Dec.,  1921) 251 

Rivista  di  Filosofia  (xiii.,  2,  April- June,  1921) 250 

(  „      3  and  4,  July-Dec.,  1921)  533 

Rivista  di  Filosofia  Neo-Scolastica  (xiii.,  5  and  6,  Sept.-Dec.,  1921)        •  532 


Vlll  CONTENTS. 

NOTES. 

BLONDEL'S  "  L'Action " 38Q 

BOSANQUET,  B. — Prof.  Broad  on  the  External  World       ....  122 

BROAD,  C.  D.—  „  „  „  -        -        -         -  122 

ERRATUM 124 

LUTOSLAWSKI,  W. — Intuition  of  Reality 331 

MACKENZIE,  J.  S. — Imaginism       ----....  535 

MIND  ASSOCIATION  :  List  of  Officers  and  Members  ....  125 

,,          ,,  :  Notice  of  Annual  Meeting       -        -        -         -        -  255 

OBITUARY  NOTICES  :  E.  Boutroux x      .  123 

»          „          -  Miss  E.  E.  G.  Jones 383 

,,  ,,          :  Sir  Henry  Jones 381 

SCHULE  DER  GEISTESKUNDE .  255 

SOCIETAS  SPINOZANA  - 334 

STEIN,  LEO. — Dr.  Lutoslawski's  Theory  of  Personality  ....  253 

STOUT,  G.  F.— A  Correction 255 


NEW  SERIES.     No.    121.]  [JANUARY,   1922. 

MIND 

A  QUARTERLY   REVIEW 

OF 

PSYCHOLOGY  AND  PHILOSOPHY 


I.— THE  PHILOSOPHICAL  RESEARCHES  OF 
MEINONG  (I.). 

BY  G-.  DAWES  HICKS. 

I  HAVE  undertaken  to  give  some  account  in  this  Journal  of 
Meinong's  contributions  to  philosophy.  It  was  a  rash  under- 
taking. For  the  task  is  one  of  peculiar  difficulty.  Had 
Meinong  made  any  attempt  to  think  out  or  develop  a 
comprehensive  metaphysical  theory,  it  would  have  been 
comparatively  easy  to  sketch  the  main  features  of  that 
theory,  and  perhaps  to  indicate  where  it  seemed  exposed  to 
attack.  But  his  speculative  genius  lay  not  in  the  direction 
of  system-building ;  and  I  suspect  he  distrusted  the  attitude 
of  mind  which  system-building  frequently  betokens.  His 
published  work,  and  it  is  amazingly  voluminous,  is  all  of  it  of 
an  extremely  detailed  kind ;  its  value  largely  consists  in  its 
resolute  thoroughness,  in  the  rare  combination  it  shows  of 
unprejudiced  observation  with  acute  inference,  and  in  the 
minute  care  with  which  he  tried  to  see  all  round  and  to  get 
to  the  roots  of  the  problems  he  handled.  Moreover,  the 
themes  he  selected  for  treatment  were  almost  always  those 
at  the  growing-point  of  philosophical  inquiry  ;  he  had  an  ex- 
traordinary facility  of  discerning  precisely  that  which  required 
to  be  wrestled  with  in  order  to  make  headway  in  philosophi- 
cal research.  As  a  writer  he  was  lucid  and  clear;  but  his 
very  persistency  in  tracking  a  subject  through  its  ramifications 
gives  to  his  mode  of  exposition  a  certain  prolixity,  which 
those  who  like  to  have  their  philosophy  served  up  to  them  in 
imagery  and  metaphor  will  be  ready  enough  to  decry  as  dul- 
ness.  Yet  his  intellectual  honesty  in  describing  the  data  with 


Z  G.   DAWES   HICKS  : 

which  he  was  concerned,  his  snbtlety  of  analysis,  his  keenness 
of  criticism  are  sufficiently  exemplified  in  everything  he  wrote. 

In  spite,  however,  of  its  difficulties,  there  is  more  need  of 
such  a  task  as  has  been  set  for  me  being  undertaken  in  the  case 
of  Meinong's  work  than  in  the  case  of  that  of  most  philoso- 
phers. For  it  is  true  to  say  that  the  different  investigations 
upon  which  he  was  engaged,  independent  of  one  another 
though  at  first  sight  they  appear  to  be,  are  not  in  fact 
unrelated,  and  that  his  various  lines  of  reflexion  have 
principles  in  common  which  it  would  certainly  be  worth 
while  to  drag  to  light.  I  can  hardly  hope  to  succeed  in 
doing  so;  but  I  may  perhaps  contrive  to  furnish  such  an 
outline  of  Meinong's  ways  of  thinking  as  may  be  serviceable 
to  those  who  have  not  as  yet  made  acquaintance  with  his 
writings.  Of  their  importance  no  one  who  is  familiar  with 
them  can  be  in  doubt ;  they  are  important  as  profound  in- 
quiries into  the  most  fundamental  of  philosophical  questions  ; 
they  are  important  no  less  as  illustrating  the  method  by 
which  philosophic  truth  is  won. 

By  way  of  preface,  I  prefix  a  few  words  of  biographical 
import.  Alexius  Meinong  was  born  at  Lemberg  on  17th 
July,  1853.  His  family  was  of  German  extraction,  and 
his  father  had  settled  on  Polish  soil  on  account  of  his  pro- 
fessional duties.  Meinong's  student  years  were  all  spent  in 
Vienna.  After  being  six  years  at  a  private  school  there,  he 
became  a  scholar  of  the  academic  gymnasium ;  and  it  was 
due  in  particular  to  two  of  his  teachers  in  the  latter  institution 
that,  contrary  to  the  original  plan  of  his  parents,  who  had 
destined  him  for  the  law,  and  despite  a  strong  inclination  on 
his  own  part  to  devote  himself  to  music,  he  decided  in  the  end 
upon  a  scientific  career.  He  entered  the  University  in  the 
autumn  of  1870,  matriculating  in  the  Faculty  of  History.  In 
the  summer  of  1874  he  took  his  degree,  having  submitted  for 
it  a  dissertation  on  Arnold  of  Brescia.  From  his  gymnasium 
days  he  had,  however,  imbibed  an  interest  in  philosophy  ;  and 
he  chose  philosophy  as  his  Nebenfach,  offering  himself  for 
examination  in  the  first  two  of  Kant's  Critiques  which,  in 
blissful  ignorance  of  their  pitfalls,  he  had  striven  to  master 
by  his  own  unaided  reading.  The  results  of  his  criticism  of 
Kant,  animated,  he  tells  us,  by  a  very  naive  radicalism,  must, 
he  confesses,  have  been  primitive  enough;  but,  without 
suspecting  it,  he  had  thus  commenced  his  life's  work.  For 
a  while  he  attended  lectures  on  law ;  but  early  in  1875  he 
resolved  to  give  himself  entirely  to  philosophy.  He  sought 
naturally  the  guidance  of  Brentano,  then  at  the  height  of 
his  influence.  That  guidance  was  unstintingly  placed  at 


THE  PHILOSOPHICAL  EESEAECHES  OF  MEINONG.      6 

his  disposal ;  and  Meinong  never  ceased  to  speak  in  the 
warmest  terms  of  his  indebtedness  to  his  teacher,1  although 
he  had  occasion  to  disclaim  the  description  of  himself  and 
Ehrenfels  as  belonging  to  the  Brentano  school.  The  first  of 
the  Hume-Studien  was  the  outcome  of  a  line  of  investigation 
which  Brentano  proposed  to  him ;  and  it  served  as  Habilita- 
tionsschrift  by  which  he  became  a  Privatdozent  in  the  Philo- 
sophical Faculty  of  Vienna  in  1878.  In  that  capacity  he 
continued  in  Vienna  four  more  years,  during  which  period 
Hofler,  Ehrenfels  and  Oelzelt-Newin  were  his  pupils.  He  was 
appointed  in  the  autumn  of  1882  (when  the  second  of  the  Hume- 
Studien  was  published)  Professor  extraordinarius  of  Philo- 
sophy at  Graz ;  and  in  Graz  he  remained  for  the  rest  of  his  life, 
refusing  repeated  calls  to  larger  fields  of  labour  (such  as  Kiel 
in  1898  and  Vienna  in  1914),  because  it  seemed  to  him  that 
here  he  would  best  succeed  in  accomplishing  the  scientific  work 
he  had  prescribed  for  himself.  He  started  at  the  University 
in  1886,  through  apparatus  provided  by  private  means,  ex- 
perimental research  in  psychology ;  and  in  1894  there  was 
instituted  in  Graz  the  first  psychological  laboratory  estab- 
lished in  Austria.  In  the  spring  of  1889,  Meinong  was 
appointed  Professor  ordinarius;  and  in  the  autumn  of  that 
year  he  married.  During  the  thirty  years  that  followed,  an 
extensive  series  of  investigations  occupied  his  activity — 
investigations  some  of  which  had  to  do  with  fundamental 
epistemological  issues,  others  that  were  of  a  psychological 
nature,  and  others  again  which  belonged  to  the  field  of 
ethics,  more  especially  to  the  theory  of  value,  to  which  his 
yearly  recurring  lectures  on  practical  philosophy  had,  in  a 
certain  measure,  afforded  the  stimulus.  Only  by  degrees 
(scarcely,  he  tells  us,  before  1900)  did  he  come  to  realise  that 
in  all  these  researches  he  had  been  moving  in  a  direction 
which  was  new  and  of  vital  philosophical  significance.  To  the 
bulky  volume  that  was  issued  in  1904  in  celebration  of  the 
tenth  anniversary  of  the  Graz  psychological  laboratory, 
Meinong  contributed  an  introductory  essay  in  which  he 
definitely  formulated,  and  endeavoured  to  determine  the 
scope  of,  what  seemed  to  him  entitled  to  be  called  a  distinct 
department  of  philosophical  science,  clearly  demarcated  from 
either  metaphysics,  or  epistemology,  or  logic,  or  psychology ; 
and  to  it  he  gave  the  name  of  Gegenstandstheorie.  After 

JFor  instance,  in  the  last  of  his  publications,  he  wrote  :  "Was  etwa  das 
Leben  nicht  mehr  zu  schlichten  vermochte,  das  hat  der  Tod  geschlichtet, 
und  vor  dem  Auge  meiner  Erinnerung  steht  als  unverlier barer  Besitz,  wie 
einst,  die  Lichtgestalt  meines  verehrten  Lehrers  in  durchgeistigter 
Schonheit,  ubergoldet  durch  den  Sonnenglanz  seiner  und  meiner  Jugend  ". 


4  G.    DAWES   HICKS  : 

1904,  much  of  his  strength  was  concentrated  upon  what  he 
regarded  as  problems  of  this  new  field  of  inquiry,  and  upon 
urging  its  claims  to  recognition.  In  1914,  he  was  elected  a 
member  of  the  Austrian  Academie  der  Wissenschaften  (he 
had  been  a  corresponding  member  since  1906)  ;  and  to  its 
Proceedings  several  of  his  latest  papers  were  contributed.1 
He  died  at  the  age  of  sixty-seven  on  27th  November,  1920, 
of  an  ailment  which  for  months  he  had  patiently  borne, 
continuing  his  academic  and  scientific  labours  until  a  few 
days  from  the  end. 

I. 

One  of  Meinong's  early  writings2  was  partly  devoted  to  a 
discussion  of  the  nature  and  aims  of  philosophical  inquiry  and 
the  position  of  philosophy  in  respect  to  the  other  sciences. 
Without  unnatural  limitation,  he  had  there  contended,  philo- 
sophy cannot  be  taken  to  denote  a  single  comprehensive 
science.  It  indicates  rather  a  whole  group  of  sciences,  linked 
together  by  a  common  characteristic.  And  the  characteristic 
in  question  is,  he  urged,  that  of  being  concerned,  either  ex- 
clusively or  at  least  in  certain  essential  respects,  with  inner 
experiences.  Not  only  psychology  itself,  but  likewise  episte- 
mology  and  logic,  ethics  and  aesthetics,  can  readily  be  brought 
under  this  point  of  view,  embarrassing  though  it  may  be  to 
find  an  exact  formula  for  the  connectedness  which  is  thus 
implied.  Even  metaphysics,  in  virtue  of  the  very  generality 
of  its  subject-matter,  is  constrained  to  bring  non-psychical 
into  relationship  with  psychical  facts,  in  order  to  maintain 
an  independent  position  alongside  of  the  natural  sciences. 

It  might  seem,  then,  as  though  Meinong  were  here  assign- 
ing to  psychology  a  dominant  position  among  the  parts  of 
philosophy  as  a  whole ;  and  so  in  a  manner  he  was.  Any 
attempt  to  proceed  in  philosophical  reflexion  by  leaving  out 
of  account  the  consideration  of  psychical  processes  is  in  itself, 
he  argued,  a  sufficiently  convincing  demonstration  of  the  in- 
herent unnaturalness  of  such  an  endeavour,  and  no  meta- 
physic  elaborated  without  regard  to  psychological  research 

1  Apart  from  the  scattered  papers  now  collected  together  in  the  Gesam- 
melte  Abhandlungen  (of  which  at  the  time  of  writing  two  out  of  the  three 
contemplated  volumes  have  appeared),  the  following  are  Meinong's  chief 
publications :  Psychologisch-ethische  Untersuchungen  zur  Werttheorie  (1894) ; 
Ueber  Annahmen  (1902 ;   a  second  and  greatly  altered  edition  in  1910) ; 
Ueber  die  Erfahrungsgrundlagen  unseres  Wissens  (1906) ;   Ueber  Moglichkeii 
und  Wahrscheinlichkeit  (1915). 

2  Ueber  Philosophische  Wissenschaft  und  Hire  Propadeutik,  1885. 


THE    PHILOSOPHICAL   RESEAKCHES   OF   MEINONG-.  5 

and  its  results  can  be  expected  to  stand.1  Such  was  his 
contention  to  the  last.  But,  as  time  went  on,  he  came  to 
draw  a  very  sharp  line  of  demarcation  between  psychology 
and  psychologism,  and  to  express  himself  as  virtually  in 
accord  with  Husserl's  well-known  polemic  against  the  latter 
in  the  Logische  Untersuchungen.  Within  the  circle  of  a 
certain  set  of  problems,  it  is,  Meinong  declared,  sufficiently 
easy  to  see  what  is  meant  by  the  term  psychologism;  it 
simply  means  psychological  methods  of  treatment  in  the 
wrong  place.  Since  knowing  is  a  mode  of  experience  (ein 
Erlebnis),  epistemology  cannot  wholly  dispense  with  psycho- 
logical methods.  Yet  over  against  the  act  of  knowing  stands 
the  known ;  knowledge,  in  other  words,  has  a  double-sided 
aspect ;  and  whoever  pursues  an  epistemological  inquiry  as 
though  there  were  only  the  psychical  aspect  of  knowledge, 
or  persists  in  forcing  the  other  aspect  under  the  point  of 
view  of  psychical  event  or  occurrence,  cannot  escape  the  re- 
proach which  the  term  psychologism  carries  with  it. 

Nevertheless,  I  am  inclined  to  believe  that  Meinong  ex- 
posed himself  to  not  a  little  misunderstanding  by  adhering  as 
he  did  throughout  to  that  early  contention  of  his  that  in 
psychology  is  to  be  discerned  the  thread,  so  to  speak,  which 
binds  the  different  parts  of  philosophy  into  such  whole  as 
they  constitute.  For  he  scarcely  meant  to  imply  more  by 
the  contention  than  that  in  the  notion  of  knowledge  is  to  be 
found  the  link  of  connexion  between  the  several  branches  of 
philosophy,  theoretical  or  practical.  In  other  words,  what, 
in  truth,  he  was  saying  was  that  there  is  not  one  group  of 
objects  specifically  entitled  to  be  called  the  subject-matter  of 
philosophy  ;  but  that  any  part  or  the  whole  of  what  is  vaguely 
described  as  the  field  of  experience  may  be  handled  philo- 
sophically if  treated  from  the  point  of  view  of  its  relation  to 
the  human  thinking  subject.  What  light  can  it  throw  on 
the  relations  in  which  the  human  mind  stands  to  the  sur- 
rounding reality  ? — such  was  the  fundamental  question  which 
philosophy  has  addressed  to  it.  And,  then,  the  special 
branches  of  philosophy  would  seem  to  be  determined  by  the 
main  differences  of  a  general  kind  which  disclose  themselves 
in  those  relations.  These  differences  would,  for  example,  be 
not  inappropriately  classified  under  the  three  heads  :  (a)  cog- 
nitive, (5)  practical,  and  (c)  aesthetic.  So  conceived,  it  is 

1  On  the  other  hand,  he  was  equally  strenuous  in  maintaining  that  the 
psychology,  be  it  never  so  experimental,  which  ruthlessly  brushes  epistemo- 
iogical  and  other  philosophical  considerations  aside  is  bound  to  become 
enbai  gled  in  crudities  and  absurdities,  which,  in  the  long  run,  will  mean  its 
undoing. 


6  G.    DAWES   HICKS  : 

obvious  that  the  treatment  of  knowledge  in  all  its  aspects 
must  form  the  central  portion  of  philosophical  science.  For 
it  is  only  in  and  through  the  process  of  knowing  that  the 
human  mind  has  a  place  at  all  in  the  scheme  of  existence; 
and,  although  the  practical  and  aesthetic  activities  are  dis- 
tinguishable from  the  knowing  activity,  they  nevertheless 
imply  the  latter  as  an  essential  condition  of  their  possibility. 
Clearly,  the  investigation  of  knowledge  divides  into  two 
diverging  lines  of  inquiry,  according  as  it  turns  upon  the 
question  as  to  the  validity  of  knowledge  or  upon  the  question 
as  to  the  way  in  which  knowing  comes  forward  as  a  natural 
process  in  the  life  of  the  individual  mind.  Furthermore, 
inasmuch  as  in  both  these  paths  of  inquiry  the  antithesis  be- 
tween the  subjective  and  the  objective  presents  itself,  yielding, 
in  the  one  case,  the  problem  of  what  meanwhile  may  be 
described  as  that  of  the  '  correspondence '  of  our  thinking 
with  reality,  and,  in  the  other  case,  that  of  the  way  in  which 
our  mental  processes  are  occasioned  or  influenced  by  external 
conditions,  the  final  issue  is  bound  to  be  raised  which  has 
been  traditionally  designated  metaphysical.  That  issue  may 
perhaps  be  expressed  thus :  What  conception  of  real  fact  are 
we  led  to  form  in  order  to  render  intelligible,  on  the  one 
hand,  the  attainment  of  truth  by  human  thinking,  and,  on 
the  other  hand,  the  conjoint  co-operation  of  mental  and  ex- 
ternal conditions  in  the  natural  world  ? 

Such,  at  any  rate,  in  broad  outline,  is  what  I  take  to  have 
been  the  essence  of  Meinong's  view  in  respect  to  the  function 
and  scope  of  the  philosophical  sciences.  Most  of  his  publica- 
tions between  the  years  1882  and  1904  had  to  do  with 
questions  which  could  not  be  exhaustively  dealt  with  either 
from  the  point  of  view  of  psychology  alone  or  from  that  of 
epistemology  alone.  And  Meinong  came  gradually  to  see 
how  both  modes  of  investigation  could  be  combined,  and 
combined  without  committing  the  blunder,  which  can  only 
lead  to  hopeless  confusion,  of  prematurely  mixing  up  the 
two  methods  and  of  drawing  upon  the  one  while  ostensibly 
engaged  in  carrying  on  an  inquiry  under  the  other. 

II. 

It  was  a  fortunate  circumstance  that  Meinong  had  been 
induced  to  devote  himself,  at  the  beginning  of  his  career,  to  a 
thorough  study  of  Hume's  theory  of  knowledge.  The  out- 
come of  his  patient  examination  of  that  theory  was  not  only 
a  valuable  piece  of  genuine  philosophical  criticism ;  it  was 
also  a  clear  discernment  of  the  exact  points  in  regard  to  which 


THE    PHILOSOPHICAL   KESEARCHES   OF   MEINONG.  7 

the  adequacy  of  the  empirical  doctrine  could  best  be  tested. 
The  Hume-Studien  disclose,  in  fact,  the  way  in  which  the 
crucial  problems  of  knowledge  originally  shaped  themselves 
for  Meinong  ;  it  is,  therefore,  advisable  to  look  at  these  Studien 
somewhat  in  detail. 

The  first  of  them  (published  in  1877)  is  concerned  with 
abstract  ideas  and  the  process  of  generalising.  The  treat- 
ment of  the  matter  by  Berkeley  and  Hume  is  submitted  to  a 
scrutiny  far  more  searching  and  penetrating  than  that  which 
T.  H.  Green,  in  his  elaborate  Introduction,  had  brought  to 
bear.  Attention  is  drawn,  for  example,  to  the  totally  different 
senses  in  which  Berkeley  employs  the  term  "sign"  when 
dealing  with  ideas  and  words  respectively  and  to  the  fact  that 
he  leaves  entirely  unanswered  the  important  question,  how  a 
general  name  is  related  to  a  general  notion.  Berkeley,  it  is 
argued,  ought  to  have  seen  that  he  had  not  disposed  of 
abstract  ideas  by  disposing -of  Locke's  account  of  their  mode 
of  origin ;  for  the  very  concessions  he  makes,  obviously  in- 
consequences in  his  exposition  as  it  stands,  would,  if  they 
had  been  followed  up,  have  forced  him  to  that  conclusion. 
Indeed,  in  more  than  one  place,  Berkeley,  it  is  pointed  out, 
was  on  the  verge  of  a  psychological  theory  that  could  have 
been  substituted  for  Locke's,  in  so  far  as  he  laid  stress  upon 
the  consideration  that  in  observing  an  individual  fact  it  lies 
within  our  power  to  concentrate  attention  upon  certain  of  its 
characteristics,  and  that  thus  its  remaining  characteristics  are 
disregarded.  Hume,  it  is  shown,  completely  misconceived 
what  he  described  as  "  one  of  the  greatest  and  most  valuable 
discoveries  "  made  in  his  time  "  in  the  republic  of  letters". 
But  the  nominalistic  view,  which  he  erroneously  took  to  be 
Berkeley's,  was  the  view  which  he  himself  tried  to  put  "  be- 
yond all  doubt  and  controversy  "  ;  and,  by  examining  in  turn 
each  of  the  negative  and  positive  arguments  employed  in  the 
Treatise  for  this  purpose,  Meinong  exhibits,  in  a  convincing 
manner,  the  failure  of  that  attempt. 

As  regards  the  negative  arguments,  the  very  formulation 
of  the  thesis  they  are  advanced  to  support  is,  Meinong  bids 
us  observe,  in  itself  extraordinary.  While  Hume's  intention 
is  admittedly  to  deny  all  abstraction,  what  he  actually  tries 
to  prove  is  that  "  the  mind  cannot  form  any  notion  of  quan- 
tity or  quality  without  forming  a  precise  notion  of  degrees 
of  each,"  as  though  it  were  not  evident,  on  the  face  of  it, 
how  many  of  the  cases  usually  taken  to  be  cases  of  abstrac- 
tion are  thereby  left  out  of  account.  But,  waiving  this  ob- 
jection, no  one  of  the  three  arguments  by  which  the  thesis 
was  to  be  put  beyond  the  range  of  controversy  will  bear 


8  G.   DAWES   HICKS  : 

examination.  Take,  for  instance,  the  third  of  them.  It  will 
be  granted,  Hume  avers,  that  everything  in  nature  is  indi- 
vidual, and  that  it  would  be  absurd  to  suppose  a  really  exist- 
tent  triangle  which  was  without  definite  dimensions.  And 
if  this  be  absurd  in  reality,  it  must  also  be  absurd  in  idea. 
Again,  "  to  form  the  idea  of  an  object,  and  to  form  an  idea 
simply,  is  the  same  thing."  If,  then,  it  be  impossible  to  form 
an  idea  of  an  object  that  is  not  possessed  of  definite  quanti- 
tative and  qualitative  degree,  there  must  be  an  equal  impos- 
sibility of  forming  an  idea,  that  is  not  limited  in  both  these 
particulars.  Meinong  has  little  trouble  in  convicting  this 
argument  of  either  a  formal  or  a  material  fallacy  ;  a  formal 
fallacy,  if  by  '  everything '  be  meant  jedes  Ding,  for  then  the 
word  '  object '  is  equivocal,  since  it  is  used  both  for  an  existent 
thing  and  for  a  content  of  presentation,  a  material  fallacy,  if 
by  '  everything '  be  meant  alles,  for  then  it  is  false  that 
everything  in  nature  is  individual.  Furthermore,  granted 
that  it  is  absurd  to  suppose  there  can  be  a  thing  in  nature 
without  its  definite  degree  of  quality  and  quantity,  granted 
that  each  thing  must  accordingly  be  perceived  as  in  this  re- 
spect a  determinate  thing,  does  it,  then,  in  the  least  follow 
that  each  idea  of  that  thing  must  necessarily  represent  all 
these  determinations  ?  An  assumption  of  that  sort  would  be 
no  less  ridiculous  than  to  maintain  that  because  an  individual 
existent  has  an  indefinitely  large  number  of  characteristics, 
the  content  of  the  notion  of  that  existent  must  be  indefinitely 
great.  In  short,  an  idea  of  an  individual  thing  is  far  from 
being  an  individual  idea ;  and  yet  except  on  the  ground  that 
the  idea  of  an  individual  thing  is  an  individual  idea,  no  in- 
ference can  be  drawn  from  the  individuality  of  things  to  the 
individuality  of  ideas. 

The  positive  line  of  argument  by  which  Hume  sought  to 
come  to  the  assistance  of  what  he  took  to  be  Berkeley's  theory 
turns  out,  in  Meinong's  hands,  to  be  no  less  unsatisfactory. 
First  of  all,  he  would  have  us  notice  the  singular  want  of 
perspicuity  characterising  Hume's  exposition.  The  problem 
is  to  explain  how  a  particular  idea  attains  in  our  reasoning  an 
application  such  as  it  would  have  were  it  universal.  The 
explanation  offered  is  that  we  apply  the  same  name  to  similar 
objects ;  and,  when  that  custom  has  established  itself,  the 
hearing  of  the  name  revives  the  idea  of  one  of  these  objects, 
the  one  wrhich  happens  casually  to  make  its  appearance  most 
readily.  Yet  what  about  the  other  ideas,  likewise  associated 
with  the  name?  "  They  are,"  Hume  replies  "  not  really  and 
in  fact  present  to  the  mind,  but  only  in  power."  But,  asks 
Meinong,  since  when?  Hume  would  appear  to  say,  since 


THE    PHILOSOPHICAL   EESEAKCHES   OF   MEINONG.  9 

the  act  of  mentioning  the  name.  A  disposition  to  revive  the 
ideas  in  question  must,  however,  surely  have  been  previously 
there,  if  eventually,  through  aid  of  the  word,  they  are  repro- 
ducible. The  situation  becomes  the  more  perplexing  when 
Hume  goes  on  to  assert  that  the  word  raises  up  besides  the  idea 
a  "  certain  custom,"  and  that  this  custom  produces  any  other 
individual  idea,  for  which  we  may  have  occasion.  Are  we,  then, 
here  to  understand  by  "  custom  "  a  permanent  indispensable 
pre-condition  of  the  last  mentioned  idea,  and  by  "  occasion  "  the 
immediate  cause  of  its  appearance  ?  If  so,  the  whole  theory 
stands  or  falls  with  what  can  be  made  out  with  respect  to 
this  "occasion".  Nevertheless,  Hume  vouchsafes  no  infor- 
mation as  to  whether  such  an  "  occasion "  must  always  be 
present  whenever  we  hear  that  wrord,  nor  is  it  easy  to  see 
wherein  the  necessity  of  its  presence  could  be  supposed  to 
lie,  although  in  its  absence  there  can  admittedly  be  no 
question  of  generality.  Hume's  lack  of  precision  just  where 
precision  is  necessary  renders  it  difficult  to  come  to  close 
quarters  with  the  theory  itself ;  but  the  moment  we  try  to 
do  so  it  becomes  manifest,  Meinong  urges,  how  little  mere  as- 
sociation without  abstraction  is  able  to  achieve.  We  have  be- 
fore us,  let  us  say,  a  round  piece  of  paper  or  a  mill-stone  (see- 
ing that,  ex  hypothesi,  we  cannot  think  of  a  circle  in  abstracto), 
and  we  call  this  "shape".  Now,  it  can  safely  be  affirmed 
that  it  would  never  occur  to  us,  so  soon  as  we  happened  to  see 
a  square  corn-field,  to  call  to  mind  that  "  shape"  and  to  give 
the  name  "  shape  "  likewise  to  the  field.  No  doubt,  if  we  were 
in  a  position  to  think  of  shape  in  abstracto,  all  would  be  plain 
sailing,  but  this  is  precisely  what  Hume  is  concerned  to  deny. 
Naturally,  the  difficulty  becomes  the  more  glaring  the  greater 
the  generality  attaching  to  the  name.  Moreover,  as  Hume 
himself  points  out,  the  same  thing  may  be  called  by  a  great 
number  of  different  names — e.g.,  mill-stone,  a  round  thing, 
a  heavy  thing,  a  material  thing,  etc.  Yet  he  has  offered  no  ex- 
planation of  how,  under  such  unfavourable  circumstances,  it 
cornes  about  that  even  the  slightest  appreciable  association  be- 
tween word  and  idea  could  be  formed.  Once  more,  and  assum- 
ing meanwhile  that  objections  such  as  the  foregoing  have  been 
surmounted,  no  sooner  is  the  effort  made  to  see  how  *  general 
ideas,'  formed  in  the  manner  supposed,  function  in  proposi- 
tions than  the  theory  breaks  down  hopelessly.  A  proposition, 
such  as  "  wolves  are  mammals,"  it  would  have  to  be  said,  is 
in  the  first  instance  an  assertion  about  words  ;  so  far  as  actual 
things  are  concerned,  the  statement  could  only  express  the 
result  of  a  perfectly  general  inference  based  on  a  similarity 
which  association  with  the  word  "  mammal  "  presupposed. 


10  G.    DAWES   HICKS  : 

But,  since  the  same  objects  are  also  associated  with  many 
other  words — e.g.,  organic  being — nothing  would  be  gained 
by  the  knowledge  of  that  similarity.  Finally,  if  account  be 
taken  of  all  that  is  usually  included  under  the  head  of  ab- 
straction, the  inadequacy  of  the  doctrine  becomes  strikingly 
apparent.  We  speak  often  enough  of  family  traits,  of  natural 
types,  of  a  literary  style,  and  so  forth ;  and,  in  doing  so,  are 
referring  to  characteristics  which  several  individuals  have  in 
common.  The  ideas  of  such  attributes  appear,  therefore,  as 
general  notions,  in  regard  to  which  scarcely  any  one  would 
dispute  that  the  common  feature  must  first  be  recognised  as 
such  before  a  name  can  be  given  to  it.  Here,  then,  quite  cer- 
tainly the  name  acquires  its  generality  through  the  notion, 
and  not  the  notion  through  the  name. 

The  two  fundamental  errors  that,  in  Meinong's  opinion, 
vitiate  Hume's  theory  are  (a)  his  failure  to  take  account  of 
the  content  or  intension  of  a  concept,  and  (6)  his  use  of  the 
doctrine  of  association  to  explain  the  way  in  which  the  con- 
cept acquires  its  extension  or  denotation.  In  ordinary  usage, 
the  terms  general  and  particular  have  reference  to  the  exten- 
sion, and  the  terms  abstract  and  concrete  to  the  intension, 
of  a  concept.  A  concept  that  is  or  can  be  applied  to  many 
objects  is  general;  a  concept  that  is  obtained  by  an  act  of 
abstraction  is  abstract.  Every  concrete  object  is  an  in- 
dividual object.  But  the  presentation  of  a  concrete  object 
includes  only  such  characteristics  as  can  be  apprehended  by 
sense  at  any  one  moment;  consequently  individual  objects 
are  known,  for  the  most  part,  in  a  form  that  is  more  or  less 
abstract.  No  doubt,  it  is  as  concrete  that  every  empirical 
datum  comes  at  first  into  consciousness ;  and,  in  so  far,  con- 
crete data  furnish  the  basis  of  knowledge.  Knowledge, 
however,  is  primarily  concerned  not  with  presentations  but 
with  their  objects.  In  knowing,  we  seek  to  liberate  that 
which  we  take  to  be  peculiar  to  the  object  from  the  contin- 
gent features  introduced  into  it  by  the  act  of  apprehending. 
Bo  that  almost  always  just  that  which  makes  the  presentation 
concrete  will  fall  away  from  it.  It  follows,  therefore,  so 
Meinong  argues,  that  while  all  general  notions  are  abstract, 
not  all  abstract  notions  are  general.  In  respect  to  the  ques- 
tion whether  a  concept  is  universal  or  particular,  the  number 
of  attributes  constituting  its  content  is  quite  immaterial; 
not  so,  however,  the  quality  of  those  attributes,  because  it 
will  be  according  as,  in  view  of  such  quality,  the  presence  of 
individual  objects,  corresponding  to  the  concept  in  question, 
be  conceived  as  mathematically  or  physically  impossible  or 
otherwise,  that  the  concept  must  be  held  to  be  individual  or 


THE    PHILOSOPHICAL   EESEARCHES   OF   MEINONG.  11 

general.  On  the  other  hand,  however,  in  respect  to  the 
question  whether  a  universal  concept  is  more  or  less  universal, 
the  amount  of  content  may,  under  certain  circumstances,  be 
a  relevant  consideration,  and  the  quality  of  the  content  al- 
ways is ;  but  neither  from  the  one  nor  the  other  nor  from 
both  alone  can  any  answer  be  given  to  the  question,  because, 
in  reference  to  extension,  we  are  concerned  with  a  relation, 
while  the  content  gives  us  only  one  term  of  the  relation,  and 
the  second  term  must  be  supplied  by  experience.  Meinong,. 
insists,  then,  that  the  extension  is  not,  like  the  intension, 
something  definitely  fixed  or  self-evident ;  but  that,  on  the 
contrary,  the  real  extension  of  a  notion  is  no  less  independent 
of  our  knowledge  than  is  any  fact  of  the  external  wrorld.  Con- 
sequently, to  suppose  that  between  general  and  individual 
idea  an  association  must  first  be  contracted  in  order  that  the 
latter  should  be  subsumed  under  the  former  is,  for  this  very 
reason,  absolutely  precluded.  In  fine,  Meinong's  argument 
is  directed  all  through  to  bringing  out  what  he  conceives  to 
be  the  truth  that  not  association  but  the  self-conscious  activity 
of  attention  is  the  main  function  involved  in  abstraction  and 
generalisation. 

The  second  of  the  Hume-Studien  (published,  as  already 
noted,  in  1882),  deals  with  the  theory  of  relations,  and  is 
much  more  constructive  than  the  first  had  been ;  Meinong 
here  elaborates  a  position  of  his  own  that,  in  view  of  his 
subsequent  work,  deserves  special  notice.  His  method,  how- 
ever, is  still  the  same  as  before.  He  still  proceeds  on  the  basis 
of  a  critical  discussion  of  what  he  finds  in  the  writings  of  Locke,. 
Hume,  and  the  later  empirical  thinkers.  As  he  had  formerly 
refused  to  recognise  in  Hume's  nominalism  a  legitimate 
development  of  Berkeley's  doctrine,  so  here  he  is  inclined  to 
defend  Locke's  common-sense  treatment  of  the  subject  under 
consideration  against  Hume's  psychical  atomism.  But  he 
does  not  fall  into  Kant's  mistake  of  supposing  it  was  only  in 
reference  to  cause  and  effect  that  Hume  had  raised  the  issue 
of  necessary  connexion ;  indeed,  it  is  not  so  much  upon 
Hume's  handling  of  causality  as  upon  his  handling  of  the 
more  elementary  relations  of  likeness  and  difference  that 
Meinong's  scrutiny  is  concentrated.  And  he  maintains  that 
Hume's  whole  theoretical  philosophy  is  so  essentially  built 
upon  his  Relationslehre  that  an  exposition  of  the  latter,  with 
any  claim  to  completeness,  would  scarcely  be  justified  in 
leaving  a  single  portion  of  the  former  out  of  account. 

At  the  outset,  Meinong  resists  the  view  (the  view  of  Mill  and 
Spencer,  but  derived  ultimately  from  Hume)  that  a  relation, 
such  as  that  of  likeness,  is  explicable  from  the  mere  presence 


12  G.    DAWES   HICKS  : 

to  consciousness  of  two  or  more  presentations,  in  this  case 
like  or  resembling  presentations.  He  takes  his  stand  at  once 
on  the  principle  laid  down  by  Lotze.  "Every  comparison, 
and  in  general  every  relation  between  two  elements,  pre- 
supposes," so  Lotze  had  asserted,  "  that  both  points  of  relation 
remain  separate,  and  that  an  ideating  activity  passes  over 
from  the  one  to  the  other,  and  at  the  same  time  becomes 
conscious  of  the  alteration  which  it  has  experienced  in  this 
transition.  We  exercise  such  an  activity  when,  for  example, 
we  compare  red  and  blue,  and  thereby  there  ensues  for  us 
the  new  presentation  of  a  qualitative  similarity,  which  we 
ascribe  to  both."1  Meinong  points  out  that  the  existence  of 
an  activity  of  the  kind  indicated  by  Lotze  had  already  been 
virtually  recognised  by  Locke,  when  he  described  relations 
as  complex  ideas  resulting  from  an  act  of  comparison,  al- 
though Locke  had  left  the  nature  of  the  act  which  he  thus 
'Specified  undetermined.  So  much  being  granted,  there  is, 
Meinong  argues,  already  determined  what  alone,  in  any  in- 
telligible sense,  can  be  called  the  fundamentum  relationis  of 
the  activity  in  question ;  clearly  it  can  be  no  other  than  the 
•compared  presentations  themselves.  No  doubt,  what,  as  a 
rule,  we  have  given  are  not  single  but  complex  presenta- 
tions, complexes  of  presented  attributes.  If  two  dice,  one 
red  and  the  other  blue,  be  compared  and  found  to  be  different, 
the  comparison,  in  the  strict  sense,  has  reference  not  to  the 
shape  but  to  the  colour ;  and,  accordingly,  only  the  actually 
'Compared  features  ought  to  be  spoken  of  as  fundamenta. 
Yet,  in  such  cases,  we  are  wont  to  say  not  merely  that  the 
two  colours  but  that  the  two  dice  have  been  compared, 
with  the  qualification,  perhaps,  "in  respect  to  their  colour  ". 
And  in  this  usage  may  be  discerned  what  Locke  had  in 
mind  when  he  insisted  that  in  a  relation  there  is  always  re- 
quisite, on  the  one  hand,  the  things  to  be  compared,  and,  on 
the  other  hand,  the  "  occasion  "  for  such  comparison.  In  the 
example  just  used,  the  dice  are  the  things,  the  colour  the 
"occasion".  Evidently,  then,  there  can  be  no  relation 
without  a  fundamentum,  or  more  precisely  two  fundamenta. 
These  may  themselves  be  relations,  for  relations  can,  of 
-course,  be  compared ;  but  we  cannot  go  on  making  relations 
the  fundamenta  of  relations  indefinitely;  ultimately  every 
relation  has  for  its  fundamenta  presentations  which  are  not 
relations,  for  otherwise  there  would  be  a  comparison  in  which 
there  was  nothing  compared.  Hume's  initial  error,  an  error 
that  ruined  his  classification  of  relations,  consisted  in  his  con- 
iusing  the  notion  of  fundamentum  with  that  of  relation. 

1  Grundzuje  der  Psychologic,  p.  23. 


THE   PHILOSOPHICAL   BESEABCHES   OF   MEINONG.  13 

Two  chief  classes  of  relations  are  distinguished  by  Meinong 
—relations  of  comparison  (Vergleichunysrelationen)  and  re- 
lations of  compatibility  (Vertrdglichkeitsrelationeri).  (a) 
Under  the  first  class  are  included  relations  of  likeness 
(Gleichheif)  and  of  unlikeness  or  difference  (Verschiedenheit). 
And  here  the  view  (e.g.,  Mill's)  that  likeness  is  only  a  special 
case  of  resemblance  (Aehnlichlceit)  is  decisively  rejected. 
Resemblance,  it  is  argued,  may  be  present  in  all  conceivable 
gradations,  but  in  likeness  there  is  no  gradation — what  is 
like  is  completely  like,  and  what  is  not  completely  like  is  not 
like — so  that  it  would  be  unnatural  to  bring  the  cases  of 
likeness  and  certain  cases  of  unlikeness  under  the  head  of 
resemblance,  and  the  remaining  cases  of  unlikeness  under 
the  head  of  difference.  Not  only  so ;  it  would  be  difficult  to 
imagine  how,  through  determination  of  the  notion  of  resem- 
blance, the  notion  of  likeness  could  have  arisen.  And  finally, 
the  usage  of  language  is  altogether  adverse  to  the  view  in 
question,  for  in  speaking  of  similarity  one  is  almost  invariably 
conscious  of  difference  as  being  likewise  involved.  Resem- 
blance, then,  is  always  a  special  case  of  difference  ;  in  so  far 
as  partial  agreement  or  likeness  is  essential  to  resemblance, 
it  is  still  only  likeness  of  elements,  while  the  resemblance  is 
asserted  of  the  whole.  Spatial  and  temporal  relations  fall 
within  this  class.  The  fundamenta  of  the  former  are  like 
and  unlike  space-determinations  within  the  homogeneous 
space-continuum,  and  of  the  latter  time-determinations  within 
the  homogeneous  time-continuum.  (5)  Meinong  was  led  to- 
constitute  relations  of  compatibility  into  a  class  by  them- 
selves through  consideration  of  what  Hume  had  meant  by 
'  contrariety '  and  Locke,  in  his  familiar  definition  of  know- 
ledge, by  'repugnancy'.  The  notions  compatibility  and 
incompatibility  are  not,  he  maintains,  constituted  after  the 
manner  of  the  notions  likeness  and  difference.  The  latter  ad- 
mit of  no  definition,  and  can  only  be  explained  by  means  of 
examples  ;  the  former  do  seem  to  admit  of  a  kind  of  definition 
— compatible  is  what  can  subsist  together,  incompatible  what 
cannot.  In  the  long  run,  the  question  of  compatibility  can 
only  be  raised  with  regard  to  attributes  of  like  time-  and 
space-determinations.  Here  we  seem  to  be  face  to  face 
with  an  ultimate  fact,  and  a  fact  which  belongs  not  to  the 
province  of  presentation  but  to  that  of  judgment.  When  it  is 
said,  for  example,  that  the  '  round '  and  the  '  square  '  cannot 
be  simultaneously  in  the  same  place,  there  is  no  new  pre- 
sented content  introduced  by  the  phrase  '  cannot ' ;  it  only 
makes  the  statement  an  expression  of  a  negative  judgment, 
and  this  judgment  carries  with  it  that  peculiar,  indescrib- 


14  G.  DAWES  HICKS: 

able,  and  familiar  characteristic  which  it  has  long  been 
customary  to  describe  as  evidence.  It  would  seem,  therefore, 
that  relations  of  compatibility  may  be  said,  in  a  certain 
sense,  to  be  secondary  formations,  in  so  far  as  they  are 
based  upon  a  special  case  of  relations  of  comparison — 
namely,  on  the  case  of  like  space-  and  time-determinations. 
There  is,  however,  a  further  feature  to  be  noticed.  The  two 
possibilities  that  come  forward  in  regard  to  this  second  class 
of  relations  do  not  stand  independently  side  by  side  as  like- 
ness and  unlikeness  do.  The  one  can  only  be  characterised 
as  the  negation  of  the  other ;  and,  moreover,  it  is  compati- 
bility that  is  the  negation  of  incompatibility  and  not  vice 
versa  ;  for  compatibility  seems  to  imply  no  more  than  that, 
in  a  particular  instance,  one  has  before  him  a  case  where 
evidence  for  an  incompatibility  of  the  kind  indicated  is 
wanting.  If  it  be  asked  why  such  different  things  as  cases 
of  comparison  and  of  compatibility  should  be  grouped  to- 
gether under  the  title  of  relations  between  presented  objects, 
Meinong  would  here  justify  his  doing  so  by  pointing  in  the 
first  instance  to  the  part  played  by  the  presented  objects, 
which  seemed  to  him  perfectly  analogous  in  the  two  cases. 
For  these  objects,  the  fundamenta,  are  invariably  the  basis 
upon  which  rest,  in  the  one  case,  the  presentation  of  likeness 
or  difference,  and  the  evident  affirmation  which  attaches 
itself  thereto  ;  and,  in  the  other  case,  the  evident  negation. 
So  that  incompatibility  and  likeness  may  each  be  said  to  be 
a  relation  between  presented  attributes.1 

Meinong  does  not  claim  that  his  two-fold  classification  of 
relations  is  an  exhaustive  classification,  although  it  does,  he 
thinks,  cover  all  the  seven  kinds  distinguished  by  Hume  in  the 
Treatise.  There  are,  however,  relations  toto  genere  distinct 
from  any  that  were  considered  either  by  Hume  or  Locke.  For 
instance,  in  quite  a  legitimate  sense,  one  may  speak  of  a 
relation  between  the  act  of  presenting  (vorstellen)  and  its 
content,  where  we  have  to  do  not  with  presented  contents 
alone  but  also  with  the  act  in  and  through  which  those 
contents  have  their  being.  And  this  relation  is  not  the 
product  of  a  new  activity ;  on  the  contrary,  in  the  appre- 
hension of  it  we  seem  to  be  no  less  passive  than  we  seem  to 
be  in  regard  to  the  data  described  as  fundamenta.  So,  too, 

1  This  contention  was  discarded  in  the  later  writings.  In  them,  Meinong 
maintains  that  relations  of  compatibility  are  based  upon  Objectives  (see 
below,  p.  26  sqq.) ;  and  that,  consequently,  they  are  relations  not  between 
presented  attributes  but  between  objects  such  as  can  only  be  apprehended 
through  judgments  or  assumptions  (c/.,  e.g.,  Ueber  Annahmen,  2te  Aufl., 
p.  215  sqq.). 


THE    PHILOSOPHICAL   EESEAECHES    OF   MEINONG.  15 

the  relations  between  the  elements  of  a  composite  presenta- 
tion are  not  in  the  least  analogous  to  the  relations  between 
the  presented  parts  of  a  physical  object.  These,  then,  are 
instances  of  what  Meinong  here  calls  "real  relations  " — real, 
because,  seeing  they  are  not  outcomes  of  a  new  activity, 
they  must  really  belong  to  the  data,  otherwise  there  could 
be  no  awareness  of  them.  At  the  same  time,  '  real,'  in  this 
context,  must  not  be  understood  as  referring  to  anything 
extra-psychical,  for  obviously  the  relations  in  question  are 
between  psychical  data,  and  are  directly  accessible  to  us  in 
a  way  in  which  relations  outside  the  circle  of  psychical 
phenomena  never  can  be.  As  contrasted  with  these  "real 
relations,"  the  relations  previously  considered  may  be  called 
"  ideal  relations  " — ideal,  because  they  are  the  products  of  a 
specific  psychical  activity,  and  do  not  belong  to  the  data  apart 
from  such  activity.  But  now,  within  the  sphere  of  "  ideal 
relations  "  a  further  line  of  demarcation  requires  to  be  drawn. 
Hume  distinguished  between  relations  that  depend  entirely  on 
the  ideas  compared  and  those  that  may  be  changed  without 
any  change  in  the  ideas.  Through  his  failure  clearly  to 
recognise  the  significance  of  fundamenta  for  a  relation,  Hume 
was  led  wrongly  to  include  contiguity  and  distance  under 
relations  of  the  last  mentioned  kind.  Yet  his  distinction 
itself  is  an  important  one  and  coincides  with  the  distinction 
upon  which  Meinong  thinks  stress  should  be  laid  between 
primary  and  secondary  relations.  The  primary  relations, 
those  of  comparison  and  of  compatibility,  are  obtained  be- 
yond question  by  an  act  of  discrimination  directed  upon  the 
given  fundamenta.  There  are,  however,  secondary  relations, 
combinations  of  special  cases  of  primary  ones,  where  relative 
determinations  without  fundamenta  come  more  or  less  to 
the  front.  With  respect  to  secondary  relations  the  data 
accessible  to  us  are  not  sufficient,  and  if  we  connect  the 
assertion  of  such  relations  with  these  data,  we  must  have 
grounds  for  doing  so  outside  the  data  themselves.  The  two 
chief  secondary  or  derivative  relations  are  those  of  causation 
and  identity,  both  of  which  have  been  acquired  originally 
as  the  result  of  practical  needs.  Meinong's  analysis  of  the 
causal  relation  is  virtually  in  agreement  with  Mill's.  He 
lays  repeated  emphasis,  however,  upon  the  consideration  that 
with  respect  to  causality  (and  the  same  is  true  with  respect 
to  identity)  it  is  impossible  to  confine  attention  to  presenta- 
tions ;  there  is  always  involved  a  reference  to  external  things, 
to  real  existents.  To  ascribe  causality  to  mere  presentations 
would,  he  says,  be  like  ascribing  a  true  biography  to  a  prince 
in  a  fairy  tale.  The  relation  of  causality  is  invariably 


16  G.   DA  WES   HICKS: 

"  earned  over  "  into  the  external  world.  And  he  tries  to  show 
that  there  is  nothing  inexplicable  in  this  reference  to  real 
existents.  When  one  says,  for  example,  of  two  feelings, 
that  prior  to  the  act  of  comparison  by  which  they  are  judged 
to  be  different  they  were  in  fact  different,  there  has  already 
been  such  a  "  carrying  over  "  of  the  ideal  relation  of  differ- 
ence from  presented  contents  to  existent  entities.  At  the 
same  time,  primary  relations  may  be  said  to  be  "pure  rela- 
tions "  in  the  sense  that  an  Uebertragung  of  this  kind  is  not 
essential  for  their  being  as  relations,  whereas  it  is  essential 
for  the  being  of  secondary  or  "  empirical"  relations.  The 
pure  relations  are,  therefore,  a  priori,  and  the  judgments 
asserting  them  are  a  priori  judgments.  But  no  judgment 
about  empirical  relations  can  rest  on  a  merely  a  priori 
basis ;  and  just  as  little  can  a  judgment  about  pure  rela- 
tions do  so  when  it  has  reference  not  merely  to  presented 
contents  but  also  to  existent  fact.  It  is  further  clear  that 
none  but  "ideal  relations"  can  be  "  carried  over  "  into  the 
domain  of  extra-psychical  reality. 

III. 

The  foundation  of  Meinong's  subsequent  work  is  laid  in 
these  early  Studies.  In  them  almost  all  the  problems  to 
which  later  he  devoted  such  unwearied  intellectual  industry 
are,  in  one  form  or  another,  indicated,  if  not  distinctly  for- 
mulated. Not  a  few  of  the  positions  which  were  here  main- 
tained came,  it  is  true,  in  the  course  of  time,  to  be  abandoned, 
and  others  to  be  radically  revised ;  and  the  reasons  that  led 
to  such  changes  often  throw  the  clearest  light  upon  the  views 
that  were  finally  adopted.  I  shall  have  something  to  say 
immediately  upon  some  of  the  principal  changes  ;  mean- 
while I  want  to  refer  to  one  definite  result  which  these 
investigations  yielded  him,  and  from  which  he  found  no 
occasion  to  deviate. 

In  his  own  way,  Meinong  had  reached  the  principle  which 
may  not  inappropriately  be  said  to  be  the  starting-point  of 
the  Kantian  theory, — the  principle,  namely,  that  knowledge 
involves  a  unique  antithesis  between  knowing  and  the 
known,  and  that  any  attempt,  such  as  Hume  had  made,  to 
dispense  with  the  former  term  of  the  antithesis  must  inevit- 
ably prove  futile  and  abortive.  In  other  words,  through  grap- 
pling with  the  crucial  questions  which  the  work  of  Hume  and 
Hume's  followers  had  thrust  upon  him,  Meinong  came  to 
see  the  necessity  of  insisting  upon  the  consideration  that 
an  object  known  never  can  be  identical  with  any  act  which 


THE  PHILOSOPHICAL  RESEARCHES  OF  MEINONG.     17 

is  a  knowing  of  it.  And  when  once  he  had  convinced  him- 
self that  all  knowledge  involves  recognition  of  relatedness 
among  the  parts  of  what  is  known,  the  existence  of  cognitive 
acts,  as  distinct  from  what  Hume  had  called  "impressions  " 
and  "ideas,"  seemed  to  him  to  be  indisputably  established. 
Let  me  try  to  illustrate  his  position  in  this  respect.  If  it  be 
said  that  the  two  presentations  A  and  B,  having  occurred, 
somehow  give  rise  to  the  new  idea  C — the  idea,  namely,  of 
their  likeness  or  difference,  such  language  only  conceals  the 
want  of  explanation  in  what  is  said.  For  there  must 
obviously  be  some  process,  some  operation  of  the  mind, 
through  which  the  production  of  C  has  come  about.  A ,  it  is 
supposed,  may  and  does  occur  separately,  B  occurs  separately. 
What  is  it,  then,  that  takes  place  when  A  and  B  are  held  to- 
gether so  as  to  admit  of  what  Hume  himself  had  vaguely 
called  "  comparison  "  ?  Now  it  is  possible — I  think  it  is  cer- 
tain— that  in  stating  the  case  in  this  way  one  is  conceding  too 
much  to  the  doctrine  one  is  opposing,  and  I  only  do  so  in  order 
not  to  go  beyond  what  Meinong  himself  would  have  said.  But 
the  point  is  that  even  on  the  assumption  that  isolated  con- 
tents, presentations,  are  thus  given,  the  inference  is  irresis- 
tible that  the  simultaneous  presence  of  these  contents,  their 
peculiarities,  their  changes,  and  so  on,  furnish  a  new  set  of 
conditions  in  response  to  which  an  inner  activity  of  the  mind 
must  have  taken  place,  if  so-called  ideas  of  relation  forthwith 
make  their  appearance.  In  so  far,  Meinong  was  but  reiterat- 
ing Lotze's  well-known  contention  ;  and  in  this  particular  re- 
ference, I  do  not  know  that  he  ever  advanced  any  considerable 
way  from  Lotze's  position.  He  did  not,  I  mean,  ever  call  in 
question  the  view  of  presentations  as  eo  many  separately 
given  units,  or  ask  himself  whether  the  separateness,  the 
singleness,  the  distinctiveness,  which  presentations,  we  will 
say,  come  to  have  may  not  be  due  to  that  very  activity  which 
he  took  to  be  involved  in  the  comparison  of  them  and  in 
discerning  their  relations.  Had  he  done  so,  not  a  few  of  the 
obscurities  that  beset,  as  we  shall  see,  even  his  mature  view 
of  cognition  would,  I  believe,  have  been  avoided,  and  he 
would  have  emerged  completely  from  the  subjectivism  of  his 
early  days. 

I  pass  now  to  consider  the  two  main  directions  in  which 
Meinong  was  led  to  see  that  the  view  of  knowledge  he  had 
hitherto  been  taking  required  modification.  These  are  not, 
in  fact,  disconnected  ;  so  soon  as  the  one  advance  had  been 
made,  it  was  well-nigh  certain  that  the  other  would  follow. 

(a)  In  the  Hume-Studien  no  distinction  had  as  yet  been 
recognised  between  the  '  content '  of  an  act  of  apprehension 

2 


18  G.   DA  WES   HICKS  I 

and  the  '  object '  (Gegenstand}  of  that  act.  Throughout,  the 
former  term  had  been  employed  as  equivalent  to  the  latter ; 
and  the  act  of  apprehending  had  frequently  been  spoken  of  as 
being  '  directed  upon '  the  content.  I  think  it  likely  that 
Meinong  was  materially  influenced  in  this  regard  by  an 
exceedingly  acute  piece  of  psychological  analysis  by  Twar- 
dowski,  which  was  published  in  1894.1  With  admirable 
lucidity,  Twardowski  pointed  to  the  ambiguity  that  attaches 
to  the  term  Vorgestelltes — an  ambiguity  in  its  way  no  less 
pronounced  than  that  which  admittedly  attached  to  the  term 
Vorstellung.  An  object  may  be  said  to  be  'presented '  in  the 
sense  that,  in  addition  to  the  many  relations  in  which  that 
object  stands  to  other  objects,  it  also  stands  in  a  definite 
relation  to  a  cognising  subject.  And,  in  this  sense,  a  '  pre- 
sented object '  is  a  veritable  object,  just  in  the  same  way  as 
an  extended  object  or  a  lost  object  is  one.  But,  on  the  other 
hand,  by  'presented  object '  may  be  meant  what  is  a  decided 
contrast  to  a  veritable  object — namely,  a  '  mental  picture  '  of 
an  object — and  then  it  is  no  longer  a  veritable  object,  is  no 
longer,  in  fact,  an  object  at  all.  That  which  is  presented  in 
a  presentation  is  its  content ;  that  which  is  presented  through 
or  by  means  of  a  presentation  is  its  object — so  Twardowski 
tried  to  bring  out  the  contrast.  In  the  paper  (published  in 
1899), 2  in  which  Meinong  himself  first  definitely  insisted  on 
the  importance  of  the  distinction,  Twardowski's  little  book  is 
specially  alluded  to  and  some  of  its  illustrations  are  used. 
The  considerations  that  had  weighed  with  Meinong  were,  he 
tells  us,  such  as  the  following.  Nothing  is  more  common 
than  to  represent  (vorstelleri)  or  to  think  of  something  which 
does  not  exist.  We  may  think  of  something  that  is  con- 
tradictory, a  round  square,  for  example,  or  of  something  that 
does  not  happen  to  exist  as  a  matter  of  fact,  a  golden 
mountain,  say,  or  of  something  which  in  virtue  of  its  nature 
cannot  exist  (likeness  or  difference  is  an  instance),  or  of  some- 
thing which  has  existed  or  will  exist  but  does  not  exist  now. 
Nevertheless,  in  all  these  cases  a  Vorstellung  exists  and  exists 
in  the  present.  Now,  argues  Meinong,  no  unprejudiced  per- 
son would  wish  to  maintain  that  the  Vorstellung  exists  whilst 
its  content  does  not.  That,  however,  is  not  the  whole  story. 
'  Content '  and  '  object '  differ  not  only  in  respect  to  existence 
but  in  respect  to  their  nature  or  character.  That  which  is 
physical  can  be  presented,  but  the  content  of  a  psychical  act 
can  only  be  psychical ;  so,  too,  qualities  such  as  blue,  warm, 

1  Zur  Lehre  vom  Inhalt  und  Gegenstand  der  Vorstellungen,  Wien,  1894. 

2  Ueber  Gegenstande  hoherer  Ordnung,  §  2,  G.  A.,  vol.  ii.,  p.  379  sqq. 


THE  PHILOSOPHICAL  BESEAECHES  OF  MBINONG.     19 

heavy,  can  be  presented,  but  neither  the  Vorstellung  nor  its 
content  by  which  these  qualities  are  presented  is  blue  or 
warm  or  heavy ;  attributes  of  this  sort  evince  themselves  at 
once  as  totally  inapplicable  to  the  contents  of  mental  acts. 
As  regards  the  relation  of  the  mental  act  to  its  content,  the 
view  which  Meinong  came  to  hold  appears  to  have  been  that 
they  are  inseparable  but  distinguishable  constituents  of  one 
existent  fact  or  event.  Whether  it  be  a  presentation  (say)  of 
a  steeple  or  of  a  causal  relation,  in  each  case  an  act  of 
presenting  is  involved,  and  qua  act  these  presentations 
resemble  one  another.  On  the  other  hand,  in  so  far  as  the 
presentations  are  presentations  of  different  objects,  they  do 
not  resemble  one  another.  And  that  wherein  presentations 
of  different  objects  are  unlike  one  another,  notwithstanding 
the  circumstance  that  as  acts  they  are  not  unlike,  is  their 
content ;  such  content,  no  less  than  the  act,  being  in  each 
case  a  psychical  existent  in  the  present,  whereas  the  object 
presented  by  means  of  it  may  be  non-existent,  not  in  the 
present,  not  psychical. 

"  The  chief  argument  against  contents,"  Mr.  Russell  once 
said,  "  is  the  difficulty  of  discovering  them  introspectively  "  ; l 
and  it  seems  often  to  be  supposed  that  whoever  speaks  of  the 
content  of  a  mental  state  is  speaking  of  something  purely 
hypothetical,  of  which  there  can  be  no  .direct  experience. 
But,  in  Meinong's  sense  of  the  term  '  content,'  it  would  be 
nearer  the  truth  to  say  that  '  contents '  are  the  only  things 
which  we  do  discover  introspectively.  For  mental  states  can 
become  known  to  us  introspectively  not  as  mere  bare  states 
or  processes,  but  only  as  specific  states, — the  awareness  of  a 
blue  colour,  for  example,  as  contrasted  with  the  awareness 
of  a  pain  or  the  awareness  of  a  wraat.  And  if  it  be  contended 
that  the  common  element,  awareness,  can,  in  all  such  cases, 
be  distinguished  from  the  specific  elements,  the  reply  is,  *'  no 
doubt  it  can ;  but  only  in  the  way  in  which  the  common 
characteristic  '  human '  can  be  distinguished  from  the  more 
specific  elements  that  belong  to  particular  individual  men — 
that  is,  by  an  act  of  deliberate  abstraction."  Now,  whatever 
else  it  is,  an  act  of  introspection  is  certainly  not  an  act  of 
deliberate  abstraction  ;  and  whoever  is  on  the  search  for 
mental  states  apart  from  their  contents,  or  for  '  contents ' 
apart  from  the  states  whose  contents  they  are,  may  well  find 
that  of  either  or  both  he  can  find  no  trace.'2  That,  however, 

1  Monist,  vol.  xxiv.,  1914,  p.  452. 

2  As  an  interesting  illustration,  it  seems  worth  while  to  mention  that, 
after  having  for  a  long  time  been  assured  of  the  existence  of  '  mental  acts  ' 
(cf ,  e.g.,  Problems  of  Phil.,  p.  65)  and  altogether  sceptical  of  'contents,' 


20  G.  DAWES  HICKS: 

is  due  to  the  fact  that  he  has  been  looking  for  something 
which  no  one  ever  supposed  to  be  there. 

(b)  Throughout  the  Hume-Studien,  Meinong  had  evidently 
been  proceeding  on  the  assumption  that  relations  must  be 
regarded  as  products  of  mental  activity.  They  might  indeed 
be  thought  of  as  '  carried  over '  into  the  physical  world  ;  but 
their  essentially  subjective  character  was  not  thereby  called 
in  question.  It  is  in  the  article  which  appeared  in  1891 1  on 
Ehrenfels'  view  of  Gestaltqualitdten  that  Meinong  is  to  be 
seen  for  the  first  time  freeing  himself  from  this  assumption. 
In  that  article  he  acknowledges  that  he  had  himself  fallen 
into  the  'psychologist's  fallacy'  of  thinking  that,  because  a 
psychical  act  is  requisite  for  the  apprehension  of  relations,  it 
is  necessary  that  reflexion  should  be  directed  on  psychical 
states  in  order  that  relations  should  be  presented.  But  he 
had  now  come  to  see  that  from  an  empirical  point  of  view 
the  attempt  to  conceive  the  presentation  of  a  relation  (such 
as  that  between  a  colour  and  extension)  as  based  upon  the  inner 
perception  of  an  act  of  comparison  instead  of  upon  the  com- 
pared elements  themselves  is  wholly  unnatural  and  contrary 
to  fact.  More  particularly  is  the  futility  of  such  an  Umweg 
apparent  when  it  is  pursued  with  respect  to  relations  of  com- 
patibility. To  suppose,  in  the  case  of  the  round  square,  that 
it  is  not  '  round '  and  '  square '  but  the  '  presentation  of 
the  round '  and  the  '  presentation  of  the  square '  which  are 
judged  to  be  incompatible  is  surely  perverse  and  non-sensical. 
No  doubt,  under  certain  conditions,  these  presentations  may 
be  judged  to  be  incompatible ;  but  '  round  '  and  '  square  ' 
are  found  to  be  incompatible  under  the  presupposition  of  like 
space-  and  time-determinations,  whereas,  to  show  that  the 
corresponding  presentations  are  incompatible,  account  would 
have  to  be  taken  of  their  mode  of  connexion.  In  the  book 
that  was  published  in  1907,  in  defence  of  the  Gegenstands- 
theorie,2  Meinong's  rejection  of  the  doctrine  in  question  is 
still  more  emphatic.  The  most  radical  form  of  the  subjecti- 
vist  interpretation  of  the  relations  of  likeness  and  difference 
would  be,  he  thinks,  that  which  took  the  former  to  be  the 
possibility  of  confusing  one  thing  with  another,  and  the  latter 
to  be  the  absence  of  that  possibility.  Now,  it  may  be  quite 
true  that  likeness  does  really  indicate  the  possibility  of  such 

Mr.  Russell  is  now  persuaded  of  the  existence  of  '  contents,'  at  least  in 
the  case  of  memory  and  thought,  and  cannot  discover  anything  correspond- 
ing to  acts  (cf.  Analysis  of  Mind,  pp.  17-18  and  20-21.) 

1  Zur  Psychologie  der  Komplexionen  und  Relationen,  G.  A.,  i.,  p.  281  sqq. 

2  Ueber  die   Stellung   der    Gegenstandstheorie   im    System   der    Wissen- 
schqften,  pp.  143-145. 


THE    PHILOSOPHICAL   BESEAECHES   OF   MEINONG.  21 

confusion  ;  bat  little  consideration  is  required  to  see  that  like- 
ness only  indicates  and  is  not  this  possibility.  In  point  of 
fact,  one  sees  this  neither  better  nor  otherwise  than  one  sees 
that  a  water-cart  is  not  a  mountain-tarn,  or  anything  else 
that  is  obvious.  And  the  best  proof  that  likeness  is  not 
identical  with  '  to  find  like '  is  simply  what  a  direct  inspection 
of  the  two  things  yields.  But  an  indirect  proof  can  easily  be 
provided  by  the  reflexion  that  red  and  orange  (say)  are  still 
like  one  another  when  they  are  not  being  compared.  The 
argument  is  carried  further  in  the  volume,  published  in  1906, 
on  the  empirical  bases  of  knowledge,1  where  it  is  contended 
that  relations  possess  not  only  validity  for  what  are  there 
designated  '  pure  objects '  but  are  transferable  from  the 
phenomenal  to  the  real.  While,  in  reference  to  our  appre- 
hension of  relations,  the  influence  of  subjectivity  need  not  be 
disputed,  yet,  it  is  argued,  what  we,  as  we  are  now  constituted, 
are  capable  of  knowing  a  priori  is  in  no  way  rendered  dubious 
through  such  subjectivity.  We  are  justified,  therefore,  in 
asserting  that  things  in  themselves  are  like  or  unlike,  etc.,  on 
precisely  the  same  grounds  as  we  are  justified  in  asserting 
that  colours  are. 

IV. 

The  two  steps  to  which  I  have  been  referring  having  once 
been  taken,  the  road  to  the  elaboration  of  a  Gegenstandstheorie 
was  a  fairly  straight  one.  The  next  stage  of  Meinong's 
advance  towards  it  consisted  in  his  coming  to  recognise  a  class 
of  objects  which  he  called  "  objects  of  higher  order,"2  a  con- 
ception, now  sufficiently  familiar,  which  was  in  fact  only  a 
further  working  out  of  the  position  that  relations  are  objective 
in  character.  Objects  of  this  class  were  found  to  be  charac- 
terised by  a  want  of  independence,  by  a  sort  of  incomplete- 
ness, such,  for  example,  as  attaches  to  the  object  'difference,' 
if  the  attempt  be  made  to  isolate  it  from  the  differing  terms. 
These  objects  are  built,  so  to  speak,  upon  other  objects  as 
their  indispensable  conditions,  the  latter  being  the  inferiora 
of  the  former,  and  the  former  the  superior  a  of  the  latter. 
The  class  of  objects  in  question  comprises  not  only  relations 
but  also  complexes ;  and,  in  the  case  of  complexes,  the  con- 
stituents, as  in  this  sense  analogous  to  the  terms  of  a  relation, 
play  the  part  of  inferiora.  But  a  complex  is  more  than  a 

1  Ueber  die  Erfahrungsgrundlagen  unseres  Wisscns,  §  21  sqq. 

2  Ueber   Gegenstdnde   hoherer   Ordnung,    G.  A.,   ii. ,   p.   377   sqq.     The 
phrase  was  not,  of  course,  a  new  one.     Meinong  points  out  that  Fechner 
had  previously  used  it.     But  Lotze  also  spoke  of  Vorstellungen  of  higher 
order  (cf.  Grundzuge  der  Fsychologie,  iii. ,  §  2). 


22  G.    DAWES   HICKS  : 

collection  of  its  constituents;  it  is  not  composed  merely  of 
a  relation  and  its  terms,  for  the  terms  in  being  related  by 
the  relation  are  at  the  same  time  related  to  it ;  and,  although 
this  involves  a  regress,  the  regress  is  not  a  vicious  one,  and 
so  creates  no  difficulty. 

The  monograph  just  cited,  published  in  1899,  may  not 
inappropriately  be  said  to  be  a  preliminary  survey  of  the 
ground  which  Meinong  spent  the  last  twenty  years  of  his  life 
in  exploring.  The  preliminary  survey  was,  however,  suffi- 
cient to  convince  him  of  the  enormous  extent  of  the  field. 
By  *  metaphysics  '  had  usually  been  understood  a  comprehen- 
sive science  having  for  its  aim  to  form  a  conception  of  the 
nature  and  ultimate  ground  of  the  universe;  and  numerous 
as  the  deceptive  hopes  that  have  been  and  are  associated  with 
the  name  may  be,  it  is  our  intellectual  shortcoming  and  not  the 
idea  of  such  a  science  upon  which  the  blame  for  the  deception 
must  rest.  Yet,  in  spite  of  the  universality  of  its  scope, 
metaphysics  falls  far  short  of  being  a  science  of  objects. 
With  the  whole  of  what  exists  it  has,  indeed,  to  do.  But 
the  whole  of  what  exists,  including  what  has  existed  and 
will  exist,  is  infinitesimal  when  compared  with  the  whole  of 
the  objects  of  knowledge  ;  and  the  fact  that  this  has  been  so 
easily  lost  sight  of  is  due,  so  Meinong  avers,  to  that  "  prejudice 
in  favour  of  the  real  "  which  has  driven  us  to  the  extravagance 
of  supposing  that  the  non-real  is  something  too  trivial  with 
which  to  concern  ourselves.  How  absurd  this  prejudice  is 
Meinong's  preliminary  survey  had  already  made  clear  to 
him.  Among  the  objects  of  higher  order,  he  had  discovered 
a  great  sub-division  of  "  ideal  objects  " — objects  which,  to 
use  his  phraseology,  subsist  (bestehen),  and  many  of  which 
are  of  tremendous  moment  for  what  exists,  but  which 
themselves  can,  in  no  case,  either  exist  (existieren)  or  be 
real  (wirklich  sein).  Similarity  and  dissimilarity  are,  for 
instance,  objects  of  this  kind ;  they  may  subsist  between 
realities,  but  they  are  not  themselves  bits  of  reality.  Never- 
theless, that  in  knowing  we  are  vitally  interested  in  these 
objects  goes  without  saying.  So,  too,  number  does  not 
exist  alongside  of  the  counted  things,  supposing  the  latter 
to  be  existents ;  and  things  that  do  not  exist  may  be  counted. 
Pure  mathematics  has  in  fact  solely  to  do  with  ideal  objects ; 
and  our  "prejudice  in  favour  of  the  real"  leads  here  to  the 
extraordinary,  although,  of  course,  not  explicitly  recognised, 
dilemma :  Either  that  to  which  my  knowing  refers  exists  in 
reality,  or  it  exists  at  least  'in  my  presentation'.  And  the 
very  word  'ideal/  in  defiance  of  its  history,  has  come  to 
stand  for  the  latter.  What  does  not  exist  outside  of  us 


THE   PHILOSOPHICAL   EESEAECHES   OF   MEINONG.  23 

must  at  any  rate  exist  within  us — this  we  take  involuntarily 
for  granted,  and  it  seldom  occurs  to  us  to  reflect  how  futile 
and  meaningless  the  subterfuge  is. 

Here,  then,  was  a  huge  Gebiet,  constituting,  as  it  seemed 
to  Meinong,  that  of  a  new  science,  of  which  only  one  portion, 
the  department  of  mathematics,  had  hitherto  had  justice  done 
to  it.  Gegenstandstheorie  he  defines  as  the  science  of  objects 
as  such,  or  of  objects  without  limitation  to  the  special  class  of 
those  that  exist,  and  of  these  latter  only  in  so  far  as  their 
nature  (their  Sosein),  irrespective  of  their  existence,  is  con- 
cerned. It  has  to  inquire,  one  might,  borrowing  a  favourite 
expression  of  Shadworth  Hodgson's,  say,  what  an  object  is 
'  known-as  ' ;  about  its  '  what '  and  not  about  its  '  that '.  Or 
it  may  be  said  to  be  the  science  of  what  can  be  known  a  priori 
about  objects,  understanding  a  priori  in  the  sense  in  which 
Meinong  uses  the  term.1 

What  is  meant  here  by  Gegenstand  ?  A  formal  definition  is, 
we  are  told,  precluded,  seeing  that  both  genus  and  differentia 
are  wanting ;  alles  ist  Gegenstand.  But  etymologically  the 
term  gegenstelien  furnishes,  at  least,  an  indirect  characteristic. 
This  term  has  reference,  namely,  to  the  experiences  through 
which  the  Gegenstand  is  grasped  or  apprehended  (erfasst), 
the  experiences,  however,  not  being  looked  upon  as  in  any 
way  constitutive  for  the  Gegenstand.  Every  inner  experience 
(Erlebnis),  at  least  every  sufficiently  elementary  one,  has  an 
object  (Gegenstand},  and  in  so  far  as  the  experience  comes  to 
expression,  ordinarily  in  words  and  sentences,  there  stands 
normally  over  against  such  expression  a  significance  or 
meaning  (Bedeutung),  and  this  is  the  object.2  In  so  far  as 
all  objects  in  order  to  be  known  must  be  grasped  or  appre- 
hended (erfassfy,  it  is  true  that  what  is  grasped  or  appre- 
hended (Erfasstes)  and  object  are  the  same.  What  is 
apprehended  can,  however,  either  be  thought  of  as  such  or 
only  as  object.  In  the  former  case,  the  relation  in  which  the 
object  stands  to  the  apprehending  subject  is  thought  of  along 
with  it.  Yet  it  is  by  no  means  necessary  that  it  should  be. 
What  is  grasped  or  apprehended  can  be  thought  of  merely  as 
object,  for,  not  only  is  the  relation  in  question  not  contained 
in  the  thought  of  the  object,  it  belongs  in  no  way  to  the 
nature  of  the  object.  Every  object  stands  in  relations  to 
other  objects ;  the  fact  that  along  with  these  relations  there 

1  Judgments  are  said  by  him  to  be  a  priori  when  they  (a)  are  grounded 
on  the  nature  of  their  objects,  (6)  evince  themselves  as  of  self-evidencing 
certainty,  (c)  hold  necessarily,  and  (d)  are  independent  of  existence.  See 
Erfahrungsgrundlagen,  p.  10. 

*Cf.  Ueber  Annahmen,  2<*  Aufl.,  p.  26. 


24  G.  DA  WES  HICKS: 

is  that  of  being  apprehended  by  a  subject  gives  to  the  object 
the  character  of  being  an  apprehended  object,  but  not  that 
of  being  an  object.  An  object  can  be  when  the  presentation 
by  which  it  would  be  apprehended  is  not ;  and  it  can  likewise 
not  be  when  this  presentation  is.1 

As  the  notion  of  object  in  general  may  in  some  measure 
be  determined  from  the  point  of  view  of  apprehension, 
so  Meinong  thinks  the  chief  classes  of  objects  may  be  char- 
acterised by  reference  to  the  chief  classes  of  apprehending  ex- 
periences (der  erfassenden  Erlebnisse).  Accordingly,  the  four 
main  classes  of  experiences — presentation  (vorstellen],  think- 
ing, feeling,  and  conation — may  be  said  to  have  corresponding 
to  them  the  four  classes  of  Gegenstdnde — Objects,2  Objectives, 
Dignitatives,  and  Desideratives — only  the  peculiar  character 
of  these  objects  must  not  be  assumed  to  be  first  constituted 
by  the  peculiar  character  of  the  experiences  by  which  they  are 
apprehended. 

(a)  The  various  species  of  Objects  may  be  brought  to  light 
by  different  modes  of  division,  but  meanwhile  I  confine 
attention  to  the  division  of  them  into  those  which  exist, 
those  which  subsist,  and  those  which  neither  exist  nor  subsist. 

That  there  are  non-existent  Objects — that  is  to  say,  Objects 
which  only  subsist — Meinong  took  to  be  indisputable.  No 
one  would  assert  that  the  difference  between  red  and  green 
exists  as  tables  and  chairs  exist ;  but  equally  no  one  would 
doubt  the  being  of  this  difference.  The  difference  between 
red  and  green  is  not,  it  is  true,  seen  as  the  colours  are  seen, 
but  then  perception  3  is  not  requisite  for  its  apprehension ; 
from  the  nature  of  red  and  green  it  is  manifest  that  they  are 
different.4  Difference  is,  in  fact,  a  superius  which  discloses 
itself  in  an  a  priori  manner  from  the  inferiora ; 5  it  is 
founded  (fundiert)  through  its  inferiora. 

Meinong  was  likewise  convinced  that  a  class  of  non- 
subsistent  Objects  must  be  recognised.  Impossible  Objects, 
such  as  a  round  square,  do  not  subsist,  nevertheless  they  are 
Objects,  so  that  we  seem  driven  to  the  apparent  paradox  of 
asserting  the  being  of  that  which  has  not  being.  Meinong's 
position  in  this  reference  is  a  difficult  one ;  but,  then,  the 
problem  which  he  was  here  up  against  is  extraordinarily 

1  For  several  reasons,  it  is,  I  think,  unfortunate  that  Meinong  should  have 
used  the  term  Gegenstand  in  this  all-inclusive  sense.     If  he  had  employed 
the  term  '  being '  with  the  comprehensive  denotation  it  has  become  cus- 
tomary to  give  to  it,   he  might  have  spoken  of   " entities"  instead  of 
"  objects,"  and  of  a  science  of  entities  instead  of  a  Gegenstandstheorie. 

2  When  translating  the  German  Objekt,  I  will  use  a  capital  O. 

3  Meinong's  view  of  perception  I  leave  over  for  discussion. 

4  C/.,  Erfahrungsgrundtagen,  p.  5  sqq.  5See  above,  p.  21. 


THE    PHILOSOPHICAL   RBSEABCHES    OF   MEINONG.  25 

difficult.  He  tried,  however,  to  meet  the  various  objections 
that  were  raised  against  his  view.  Little  weight  could,  he 
thought,  be  laid  on  the  argument  that  the  Objects  which  he 
regarded  as  non-subsistent  must,  in  truth,  be  subsistent, 
seeing  that  they  can  be  the  subjects  of  true  and  therefore 
subsistent  propositions.  For  obviously  it  is  an  argument 
which  cannot  be  used  by  those  who  deny  that  there  are  non- 
subsistent  Objects.  If,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  a  kind  of  being 
must  belong  to  the  round  square,  because  subsistence  cannot 
be  denied  to  certain  propositions  based  upon  it,  that  is  an  argu- 
ment/or Objects  such  as  a  round  square  and  not  an  argument 
against  them.  And  to  Mr.  Kussell's  contention  that  the  ad- 
mission of  impossible  Objects  involves  denying  the  law  of  con- 
tradiction (the  round  square  can  be  asserted  to  be  both  round 
and  not  round),  his  answer  was  that  the  law  of  contradiction 
had  never  been  asserted  except  of  the  actual  and  the  possible, 
and  that  whether  it  holds  likewise  of  the  impossible  requires 
at  least  special  scrutiny.1  Meinong  saw,  at  all  events,  that 
the  problem  is  a  real  one  and  faced  it  seriously,  whereas 
usually  it  is  conveniently  thrust  aside  as  though  it  were  no 
problem  at  all. 

There  is,  however,  a  further  difficulty  with  respect  to  this 
class  of  objects,  about  which  I  should  like  to  say  a  few 
words.  It  arises  in  reference  to  the  first  division  of  them,  of 
which  I  have  not  as  yet  spoken.  What  reason  is  there,  on 
the  view  Meinong  was  taking,  for  supposing  that  there  are 
Objects  which  not  only  subsist  but  exist  ?  Meinong  himself 
distinguished  between  these  two  kinds  of  being  by  pointing 
out  that  what  exists  must  exist  at  some  definite  period  of 
time,  whereas  what  merely  subsists  is  timeless,  although 
existence  as  such  is  as  timeless  as  subsistence.2  And  his 
pupil  Ameseder,  who  usually  follows  him  closely,  adds  the 
further  differentiation  that  "  that  only  is  real  (or  existent) 
which  can  operate  causally  ".3  Meinong  certainly  seems  to 
imply  that  sense-data  (Empfindungsgegenstande)  do  not  exist. 
These  '  homeless  objects '  (so  described  because  hitherto  they 
had  formed  part  of  the  subject-matter  of  no  science)  are,  he 

1  Ueber  die  Stellung  der  Gegenstandatheorie,  p.  16.  In  his  review  of  this 
book  (MiND,  N.S.,  xvi.,  p.  439),  Mr.  Russell  urges  that  the  reply  "seems  to 
overlook  the  fact  that  it  is  of  propositions  (i.e.,  of  'Objectives'  in 
Meinong's  terminology),  not  of  subjects,  that  the  law  of  contradiction  is 
asserted  ".  I  do  not  see  that  Meiuong's  remarks  give  countenance  to  this 
supposition.  He  appears  to  me  to  be  saying  that  to  suppose  that  two  con- 
tradictory propositions  can  both  be  true  may  not  be  inadmissible  when 
their  subjects  are  impossible  Objects. 

2CY.,  Ueber  Aniiahmen,  2**  Aufl.  p.  75. 

3  Untersuchunye7i  zur  Gegenstandstheorie,  p.  79. 


2(5  G.   DA  WES   HICKS  : 

insists,  neither  mental  nor  physical.  Colours,  for  example, 
are  not  mental ;  acts  of  seeing  them  are,  of  course,  mental, 
and  so  likewise  are  the  contents  of  these  acts ;  but  colours 
are  quite  distinct  from  presentations  of  colours.  Nor  are 
they  physical ;  their  substitutes  in  the  material  world  are 
vibratory  motions  or  modes  of  energy.1  Ameseder  definitely 
affirms  that  "  since  a  colour  is,  like  every  other  object  of 
sensation,  not  capable  of  operating  causally,  its  being  is  not 
existence".  Every  sensation,  he  contends,  has  a  cause,  but 
this  cause  is  never  identical  with  what,  through  the  sensation, 
is  apprehended.  The  cause  is  physical,  or,  at  any  rate,  not 
psychical ;  what  is  apprehended  through  the  sensation,  the 
sense-datum,  is  neither  physical  nor  psychical,  and  is  not 
an  existent.2  Sense-data,  then,  being  excluded,  what  are 
the  existents  that  can  be  said  to  be  Objects,  in  Meinong's 
sense  of  Vorstellungsgegenstdnde  ?  As  instances  of  existents, 
Ameseder  mentions  a  quantum  of  water  and  a  psychical 
process.  But  the  water,  as  distinct  from  the  sense-data 
erroneously,  as  he  thinks,  ascribed  to  it,  is  not  presented, 
and  can  only  be  known,  if  at  all,  through  perception,  per- 
ception being  in  Meinong's  view  always  an  act  of  judging. 
Physical  existents,  one  would  gather,  therefore,  never  can 
be  Objects  (Objekte).  And  the  same  would  appear  to  be 
true  of  psychical  processes,  for  they,  too,  according  to  the 
theory,  cannot  be  presented.  So  that  it  would  seem  as 
though  we  were  driven  to  the  conclusion  that  for  human 
knowledge,  at  any  rate,  there  are  no  existent  Objects.  It  is 
here,  I  think,  that  we  come  upon  one  of  the  weaknesses  of 
Meinong's  doctrine  of  Vorstellungen. 

(6)  His  view  of  Objectives  has  become  sufficiently  familiar 
from  Mr.  Russell's  discussions  of  it.  If  by  a  "  proposition  " 
be  meant  not  a  form  of  words  which  expresses  what  is  either 
true  or  false,  but  that  which  is  expressed  by  the  form  of 
words,  that  which  is  true  or  false,  an  Objective  is  equivalent 
to  a  proposition.  Meinong  himself  preferred  to  say  that  a 
sentence  is  an  expression  of  an  act  of  thinking  (an  act  of 
judging  or  assuming)  and  has  a  meaning;  and  that  the 
meaning  is  the  Objective,  i.e.,  the  object  of  the  act  of 
thought.  Just  as  it  is  a  characteristic  of  every  Vorstellung 
to  present  an  Object,  so  it  lies  in  the  nature  of  every  act  of 
thought  to  think  an  Objective.  By  employing  the  term 
'  Objective '  Meinong  wished  to  emphasise  that  what  is 
judged  or  supposed  is  not  an  ideal  construction  on  the  part  of 

1  Ueber  die  Stellung  der  Gegenstandstheorie,  pp.  8-9. 

2  Untersuchungen  zur  Gegenstandstheorie,  pp.  94  and  481-482. 


THE   PHILOSOPHICAL   EESEAECHES    OF   MEINONG.  27 

the  mind  ;  that  it  is  not  the  content  of  an  act  of  thought  any 
more  than  a  presented  object  is  the  content  of  a  presentation  ; 
that  it  is  what  thought  discovers  and  not  what  thought  may  be 
supposed  to  make  or  manufacture.  Objectives  must  clearly  be 
''objects  of  higher  order,"  and  as  such  they  are  founded 
(fundiert}  upon  other  objects — that  is  to  say,  either  directly 
or  indirectly l  upon  Objects.  Confining  attention  at  present 
to  acts  of  judgment  (i.e.,  omitting  Annahmen),  we  may  say 
that  the  Objective  is  what  is  judged  (ivas  geurteilt  wird),  and 
the  Object  what  is  judged  about  (was  beurteiltwird).  If,  for 
example,  it  be  asserted  that  the  fire  is  bright,  the  Objective  is 
"that  the  fire  is  bright,"  and  this  Objective  is  founded  upon 
the  Objects  "  the  fire  "  and  "  brightness  ".  Objectives  are,  of 
course,  incapable  of  existence,  but  only  false  Objectives  are 
incapable  of  subsistence.  In  his  latest  writings,  Meinong  was 
in  the  habit  of  saying  that  every  object  has  being  (or  non- 
being)  ;  that  there  are,  however,  objects  which  not  only  have 
being  (in  this  widest  sense)  but  also  are  being,  and  that  these 
are  Objectives,  while  what  has  being,  and  is  not  being,  is 
thereby  characterised  as  Object.  Or,  expressed  otherwise, 
Objectives  attach  to  Objects,  and  Objects  stand  in  Objectives. 
What  exactly  is  to  be  understood  by  the  non-being  of  false 
Objectives  is,  he  admitted,  a  matter  that  requires  investiga- 
tion. Naming  it  meanwhile  Aussersein,  what  remains  un- 
decided is  whether  this  Aussersein  is  a  determination  of 
being  or  whether  it  denotes  simply  deprivation  of  being. 
The  principle  of  Occam's  razor  and  the  circumstance  that 
Aussersein  has  no  negative  seemed  to  him  to  favour  the 
latter  alternative,  although  he  recognised  the  difficulty  of  the 
position.2 

Being,  taken  in  the  widest  sense  as  that  which  comes 
before  us  in  every  Objective,  evinces  itself  either  as  being  in 
the  narrower  sense,  expressed  in  the  form  "A  is";  or  as 
being  so-and-so  (Sosein),  "A  is  B  "  ;  or  as  co-being  (Mitseiri), 
"If  A,  then  B  ".  These  correspond  more  or  less  to  the  dis- 
tinctions recognised  by  traditional  logic  between  so-called  exis- 
tential, categorical,  and  hypothetical  judgments.  [Whether 
there  is  any  class  of  Objectives  corresponding  to  the  dis- 
junctive judgment  of  traditional  logic  Meinong  considered  to 
be  doubtful ;  it  would  rather  seem,  he  suggested,  that  we 
have  here  to  do  with  complexes  of  Objectives,  such  as  may  be 

1  The  Objective  of  one  act  of  thought  can,  of  course,  be  founded  upon 
:m  Objective  of  another,  e.g.,  'it  is  certain  that  A  is  J3,'  where  what  is 
judged  to  be  certain  is  neither  A  nor  B  but  '  that  A  is  B  '. 

2  The  difficulty  is  not,  of  course,  peculiar  to  Meinong's  view.     On  no 
theory,  so  far  as  I  can  see,  has  any  satisfactory  explanation  been  given  of 
what  Meinong  called  "false  Objectives". 


28  G.   DAWES   HICKS  : 

met  with  in  each  of  the  three  classes  mentioned.]  Since 
both  S.osein  and  Mitsein  necessarily  involve  a  bifurcation  of 
inferiora,  these  inferiora  exhibit  themselves  in  characteristic 
relations — the  relation  of  predication  in  the  case  of  Sosein, 
that  of  implication  in  the  case  of  Mitsein.  Sosein,  again, 
falls  into  the  sub-divisions  of  Wassein  (e.g.,  "  the  horse  is  a 
mammal  ")  and  Wiesein  (e.g.,  "  snow  is  white  ")  ;  and  Mitsein 
appears  to  be  differentiated  into  the  cases  where  the  inferiora 
stand  in  an  "  if-relation  "  and  those  where  they  stand  in  a 
"  because-r elation  ". 

Meinong  held  further  that  the  peculiarity  of  the  being  of 
Objectives  is  manifested  in  nothing  more  decidedly  than  in 
the  modal  qualities  which,  as  he  maintained,  belong  to  it. 
Actuality  (Tatsdchlichkeit) ,x  the  quality  of  being  a  fact,  can 
be  ascribed  only  to  Objectives,  or  to  other  objects  only  in 
a  derivative  sense.  And,  on  purely  empirical  grounds,  Mei- 
nong was  convinced  that  when  we  are  thinking  of  the 
factual  character  of  an  Objective  we  need  not  be  thinking  of 
the  certainty  and  evidence  in  the  judgment  which  grasps  it. 
Certainty  and  evidence  are  subjective  characteristics, — the 
one  belonging  to  the  act  of  judging  and  the  other  to  its 
content;  and,  although  we  may  come  to  be  aware  of  the 
factual  character  of  an  Objective  by  reflecting  on  the 
certainty  and  evidence  of  the  judgment,  we  are  usually 
aware  of  it  by  direct  inspection.  Possibility  is,  so  to  speak, 
actuality  of  a  lower  grade,  actuality  is  the  maximum  of 
possibility ;  so  that  the  various  degrees  of  possibility  might 
be  represented  on  a  line  the  opposite  ends  of  which  would  be 
actuality  and  non-actuality.  So,  too,  necessity  is  a  charac- 
teristic of  many  Objectives,  a  characteristic  which  is  grasped, 
Meinong  maintained,  by  what  he  called  rational  evidence,  but 
which  is  in  no  sense  constituted  thereby.  The  characteristic 
of  necessity,  when  it  belongs  to  an  Objective,  is  knowable  in 
the  most  direct  and  immediate  way;2  it  is  given  as  some- 
thing essentially  positive,  so  that  the  interpretation  of  it  as 
the  inconceivability  of  the  opposite  is  ruled  out  on  this 
account  alone.  Not  only  so.  Necessity  cannot  be  taken  to 
be  an  enhanced  degree  of  actuality,  as  the  latter  is  an  en- 
hanced degree  of  possibility,  for  actuality  does  not  admit  of 
enhancement.  And,  on  the  other  hand,  it  is,  in  strictness, 
no  less  absurd  to  speak  of  a  decrease  of  necessity,  out  of 
which  decrease  actuality  could,  as  it  were,  result.  For  even 

1  If  Tatsachlichkeit  be  rendered  here  by  '  actuality,'  actuality  must  not 
of  course  be  taken  to  signify  existence. 

2  Cf.  the  opening  pages  of  Erfahrungsgrundlagen. 

3  Ueber  MogliMeit  und  Wahrscheinlichkeit,  p.  122  sqq. 


THE  PHILOSOPHICAL  EESEAECHES  OF  MBINOKG.     29 

within  the  region  of  merely  possible  Objectives  necessity  is 
likewise  to  be  found.3 

(c  and  d.)  Presentation  and  thought  are,  however,  far 
from  being  the  only  means  by  which,  as  Meinong  conceived, 
objects  (Gegenstdnde)  can  be  experienced  by  a  conscious  mind. 
No  doubt  the  capacity  of  feeling  as  a  medium  of  knowledge 
falls  a  long  way  behind  that  of  presentation.  Yet  when,  for 
instance,  we  pronounce  a  degree  of  warmth  to  be  pleasant, 
it  is  easily  seen,  he  urged,  how  utterly  foreign  it  would  be  to 
experience  to  interpret  the  quality  pleasant  as  being  an  ex- 
perienced feeling  produced  in  us  by  the  warmth.  So,  too,  he 
contended,  the  heavens  are  called  beautiful  in  no  other  sense 
than  that  in  which  they  are  called  blue,  save  that  the  ex- 
perience (Erlebnis)  through  which  the  former  of  these  qualities 
comes  to  recognition  does  not  play  in  the  inner  life  merely 
the  part  of  being  a  mode  of  grasping  or  apprehending.  But, 
all  the  same,  it  does  play  that  part ;  and,  consequently,  there 
stand  over  against  the  feelings  special  kinds  of  objects,  pre- 
cisely as  there  do  over  against  presentations  and  thoughts. 
These  objects  are  always  objects  of  higher  order ;  and  are, 
therefore,  akin  to  Objectives.  Meinong  distinguished  four 
classes  of  feelings — namely,  those  accompanying  (i)  the  act  of 
presentation,  (ii)  its  content,  (iii)  the  act  of  thought,  and  (iv) 
its  content ;  and  he  tried  to  show  that  to  each  of  these  a 
specific  kind  of  object  could  be  correlated — namely,  the 
qualities  pleasant,  beautiful,  true,  and  good  (provided  that 
not  only  a  cognitive  but  a  feeling  significance  be  ascribed  to 
the  term  '  true ').  These  values,  then,  are  distinctively  objects 
(e.g.,  when  we  say  '  this  ornament  is  pretty  '  we  imply  that  it 
deserves  to  please,  that  it  is  worthy  of  being  regarded  as 
pleasure-giving) ;  they  are  grasped  through  or  by  means  of 
experiences,  as  all  other  objects  are,  but  in  their  essence  they 
are  independent  of  such  experiences ;  and  as  such  they  are 
what  he  designated  Dignitatives.  So,  too,  in  desire,  that 
which  is  desired  is  grasped  through  or  by  means  of  the  con- 
tent of  the  act  of  desiring,  but  it  is  not  constituted  thereby. 
To  this  class  of  Desideratives,  may  be  reckoned  objects  that 
fall  under  the  heads  of  Sollen  and  ZwecJc. 

In  the  manner  I  have  thus  tried  briefly  to  sketch,  Meinong 
contrived  to  map  out  broadly  the  province  of  Gegenstands- 
theorie,  and  to  carry  out  in  several  of  its  departments  re- 
searches of  a  far-reaching  kind.  It  may  be  objected  that  a 
province  of  these  dimensions  must  certainly  be  co-extensive 
with  the  whole  of  philosophy,  if  not  with  the  whole  of  know- 
ledge. Meinong  thought  otherwise.  It  is  clearly  possible, 
he  maintained,  to  deal  separately  with  the  general  properties 


30     G.  DA  WES  HICKS  :    MEINONG'S  PHILOSOPHICAL  EESEAKCHES. 

of  objects,  to  consider  what  can  be  ascertained  a  priori  from 
their  nature,  without  reference  to  their  existence  or  non-ex- 
istence. So  regarded,  it  seemed  to  him  that  Gegenstands- 
theorie  belongs  to  philosophy  as  an  essential  part  of  it ;  and 
that  it  in  no  way  encroaches  upon  those  parts  of  philosophy 
already  recognised.  That  his  investigation  of  its  problems 
led  him  to  important  inquiries  in  other  fields,  particularly  in 
the  fields  of  psychology  and  the  theory  of  knowledge,  I  shall 
try  to  show  in  a  second  article. 

(To  be  continued.) 


IL— CONCERNING   "TRANSCENDENCE"  AND 
"BIFURCATION". 

BY  KOY  WOOD  SELLARS. 

AT  the  present  moment,  a  division  in  the  ranks  of  realism  of 
major  significance  is  making  itself  increasingly  apparent.  On 
the  one  hand,  we  have  the  advocates  of  neo-realism,  which 
is  a  form  of  naive  realism ;  on  the  other,  the  protagonists  of 
critical  realism.  Both  groups  agree  on  the  primary  principle 
of  realism  that  the  object  of  knowledge  is  independent,  as 
regards  its  existence  and  nature,  of  the  act  of  knowledge. 
But  they  differ  as  to  the  location  of  the  object  and  the  char- 
acter of  knowledge.  This  difference  is  usually  expressed  by 
the  contrast  between  transcendence  and  immanence.1  The 
critical  realist  holds  that  physical  things  and  other  minds 
transcend  the  mind  of  the  knower,  while  the  neo-realist  is 
convinced  that  they  are  directly  given  to  his  mind. 

It  is  impossible  to  make  this  contrast  accurate  apart  from 
detailed  statements  of  the  meaning  given  to  such  terms  as 
mind  and  experience.  But  I  feel  that  I  can  take  it  1'or 
granted  that  the  difference  between  the  two  groups  in  this 
respect  is  well  known.  The  neo-realist  accepts  a  compresence 
of  knower  and  known  in  the  cognitive  experience  and  thus 
makes  experience  literally  include  subject  and  object.  The 
critical  realist,  on  the  contrary,  denies  that  the  existent  which 
is  made  the  object  of  knowledge  can  be  brought  into  the  field 
of  experience. 

This  contrast  may  be  expressed  by  the  terms  epistemo- 
logical  dualism  and  epistemological  monism;  and,  again,  by 
the  distinction  between  knowledge  as  apprehension  and  know- 
ledge as  a  claim  made  for  ideas,  a  reference  of  ideas  or  pre- 
dicates to  an  affirmed,  transcendent  existent. 

The  distinctive  feature  of  critical  realism  is,  accordingly, 
its  defence  of  transcendence  and  correspondence  in  the  face 
of  the  unanimous  opposition  of  neo-realism,  pragmatism  and 

1 1  note  that  Prof.  Perry  has  adopted  this  contrast  in  a  recent  review  of 
Essays  in  Critical  Realism. 


32  EOY   WOOD    SELLAES: 

idealism.  It  claims  to  have  made  new  analyses  which  justify 
it  in  this  rather  daring  stand.  Those  who  really  desire  to 
see  philosophy  advance  will  surely  take  the  trouble  to  make 
a  serious  effort  to  understand  the  critical  realist  and  will  not 
content  themselves  with  saying  that  the  refutation  of  Locke's 
copy  theory  has  settled  the  question  once  for  all. 

In  his  recent  Gifford  Lectures,  Prof.  Alexander  has  devoted 
a  few  pages  to  a  criticism  of  the  form  which  the  doctrine  of 
a  transcendent  existent  conditioning  presentations  has  taken 
with  Stout  and  Kiilpe.  I  shall  concern  myself  with  my  own 
reaction  to  Alexander's  arguments,  leaving  Stout  to  defend 
himself.1 

Alexander  quotes  Stout  as  follows  :  "we  must  assume  that 
the  simplest  datum  of  sense- perception  from  which  the  cogni- 
tion of  an  external  world  can  develop  consists  not  merely  in 
a  sensuous  presentation,  but  in  a  sensuous  presentation  appre- 
hended as  conditioned  by  something  other  than  itself  ".2  To 
this  assertion  he  replies  that  the  "  reference  is  to  the  object, 
that  is  to  the  presentation  itself ;  for  the  theory  under  con- 
sideration the  reference  is  to  something  beyond  and  behind 
it".  Now  my  own  analysis  is  nearer  Alexander's  than 
Stout's.  I  find  two  elements  in  perception,  the  affirmation 
of  an  object  and  the  appearance  of  that  object.  I  do  not  find 
this  sense  of  conditioning  to  which  Stout  refers.  But  my 
objection  to  Alexander's  attitude  is  that  he  is  satisfied  with 
immediate  experience.  But  why  should  philosophy  be  any 
more  satisfied  with  immediate  experience  than  is  science? 
For  science,  immediate  experience  is  the  point  of  departure 
and  not  the  conclusion.  All  facts  must  be  taken  into  con- 
sideration before  the  final  synthesis  is  made.  In  all  my 
writings,  I  have  argued  that  naive  realism  is  the  point  of  de- 
parture and  that  reflexion  breaks  it  down  and  forces  us  to 
make  the  distinction  between  presentation,  or  datum,  and 
thing.  I  believe  that  this  was  Kiilpe's  position,  and  I  know 
that  it  is  the  position  of  the  American  group.  The  distinction 
we  have,  and  there  is  nothing  self-contradictory  in  it. 

Now  Alexander  does  not  believe  that  reflexion  forces  us  to 
make  this  contrast,  and  he,  therefore,  remains  a  nai've  realist. 
For  the  subtle  way  in  which  he  carries  through  the  distinction 
between  object  and  thing  I  have  the  greatest  admiration  ;  but 
I  am  convinced  that  the  facts  of  science  indicate  that  the 
datum,  or  content,  of  perception  is  subjective  or  bound  up 
with  the  percipient  organism  and  that  the  various  appear- 

1 1  understand  that  Kiilpe's  more  constructive  work  is  in  process  of  pub- 
lication under  Messer's  editorship. 

2  Alexander,  Space,  Time  and  Deity,  vol.  ii.,  p.  96. 


CONCERNING   "  TEANSCENDENCE  "   AND   "  BIFUECATION  ".      33 

ances  of  things  cannot  be  harmonised  without  reference  to 
this  fundamental  condition.1 

The  desperate  attemps  which  nai've  realists  make  to  meet 
the  traditional  objections  is  clearly  motivated  by  the  belief 
that  the  choice  is  between  naive  realism  and  idealism.  The 
assumption  that  a  non-presentative  theory  of  knowledge 
cannot  be  carried  through  controls  the  direction  of  their 
thought.  The  American  new  realists  have  acknowledged 
this,  and  Alexander  makes  essentially  the  same  confession  on 
page  98:  "How  can  experience  warrant  a  reference  to 
this  something  conditioning  presentation  which  we  never 
have  experienced  and  which  is  only  a  symbol  for  the  non- 
mental?  .  .  .  But  the  supposed  condition  of  presentation 
cannot  be  further  known  for  it  is  not  known  at  all."  But  is 
this  not  to  assume  that  knowledge  must  be  a  presentation  or 
an  experiencing?  It  is  at  this  point  that  dogma  enters. 
Certainly,  knowledge  must  be  based  upon  experience ;  but 
what  right  has  any  thinker  to  assert  that  the  thing  known 
must  be  given  in  experience,  must  be  an  existential  component 
of  experience  ? 

Critical  realism  is  an  attempt  to  devolop  a  non-presentative 
view  of  knowledge.  It  seems  advisable  to  use  this  negative 
phrase  at  the  beginning  in  order  to  avoid  the  historical 
associations  which  a  term  like  "  representative  "  inevitably 
has.  But,  first  of  all,  let  me  insist  that  there  are  different 
kinds  of  knowledge.  There  is  knowledge  of  what  is  immanent 
in  experience  such  as  ideal  objects,  sense-data,  feelings,  etc. ; 
and  there  is  knowledge  of  what  is  transcendent  to  the  in- 
dividual knower.  Without  the  first,  we  could  not  have  the 
second.  There  are,  of  course,  many  points  of  interest  in 
regard  to  the  first  kind  of  knowledge  but  I  must  neglect  them 
for  the  sake  of  concentration  upon  the  second  kind  of  know- 
ledge, which  has  so  often  been  denied  and  misunderstood — 
denied,  I  believe,  because  misunderstood. 

One  reason  for  this  misunderstanding  of  non-presentative 
knowledge  was  the  confusion  of  epistemology  with  meta- 
physics so  long  prevalent.  Epistemologicai  dualism  was 
associated  with  metaphysical  dualism  and  was  actually  hope- 
lessly entangled  with  such  assumptions  as  "mind  and 
matter"  and  "substratum  with  inherent  qualities".  Let 
it  be  borne  in  mind,  therefore,  that  the  critical  realist  is 
concerning  himself  with  the  individual's  knowledge  of 
objects  in  his  environment  which  are  obviously  not  himself 

1  This  is  quite  obviously  not  the  place  to  go  into  details  in  criticism  of 
naive  realism.  May  I  refer  to  my  examination  of  it  in  Critical  Realism > 
ch.  i.,  and  to  Drake's  arguments  in  Essays  in  Critical  Realism  ? 

3 


34  EOY  WOOD   SELLAKS: 

and  yet  not  in  another  world  in  any  metaphysical  sense.  To 
use  Whitehead's  terminology,  the  critical  realist  maintains 
that  the  "  situation  "  of  sense-objects  is  the  percipient  event, 
the  body  of  the  percipient,  the  nervous  system,  while  the 
"  situation"  of  physical  objects  is  in  the  extra-bodily  event. 
I  shall  try  to  show  later  that  this  reflective  assignment  does 
not  involve  either  "bifurcation  "  or  Aristotle's  view  of  matter. 
With  Whitehead's  philosophy  of  nature  I  have  almost  com- 
plete sympathy  but  I  do  think  that  it  can  be  separated  from 
naive  realism.1 

Lockian  realism  is  a  thwarted  naive  realism  controlled  by 
scholastic  metaphysics.  There  is  in  it  no  adequate  attempt 
to  reinterpret  the  act  and  content  of  knowledge.  He  is  con- 
vinced that  the  physical  thing  and  the  ideas  in  the  "  mind  " 
of  the  percipient  cannot  be  identical,  that  the  situation  of  the 
latter  is  not  that  of  the  former ;  but  his  stress  upon  causal 
relations  leads  him  to  forget  the  knowledge-claim  and  to  fall 
back  on  a  mere  statement  of  partial  likeness.  In  my  own 
essay  in  our  co-operative  volume  I  have  tried  to  explain  this 
point.  Thus,  though  an  epistemological  dualist,  I  can  heartily 
agree  with  Whitehead  when  he  says  that  science  concerns 
itself  with  nature  as  known.  But  is  not  nature  a  condition 
of  its  being  known  ?  We  must  supplement  the  physiological 
theory  of  perception  with  an  analysis  of  knowledge  and  its 
claims,  and  that  is  what  Locke  failed  to  do  in  any  adequate 
way.  Even  for  Whitehead,  knowledge  is  an  ultimate  claim 
and  mystery.  He  simply  knows  that  "nature  is  what  we  are 
aware  of  in  perception  ". 

The  critical  realist  holds  that  he  finds  the  act  of  knowledge, 
whether  at  the  level  of  perception  or  of  critical  scientific  judg- 
ment, is  a  claim  to  grasp  in  some  measure  the  character  and 
relations  of  its  object.  Now  this  object  is,  as  Stout  holds,  the 
condition  of  the  presentation  in  perception  but  knowledge  does 
not  directly  concern  itself  with  that  fact  but  with  affirming 
and  grasping  its  object.  The  two  things  must  not  be  confused. 
They  do  not  contradict  each  other ;  they  are  simply  different. 

The  difference  between  naive  and  critical  realism  as  theories 
of  knowledge  is  accordingly  this :  naive  realism  believes  that 
the  object  affirmed  or  referred  to  is  given — existentially  or 
literally  given  in  the  field  of  experience — while  the  critical 
realist  holds  that  the  object  to  which  his  organism  is  re- 
sponding and  which  he  affirms  is  not  so  given  but  that  the 

1  May  I  in  this  connexion  state  that  my  Evolutionary  Naturalism  which 
has  been  so  long  delayed  in  the  press  will  come  out  this  Fall  ? 

2  No  critical  realist  has  a  naive,  substantialistic,  soul-like  idea  of  mind. 
It  is  a  term  for  operations  and  contents  with  specific  situations. 


presentation  which  is  given  is  both  instinctively  and  re- 
flectively assigned  to  the  object.  It  is  the  cognitive  reaching 
out  to  or  grasping  of  the  object  which  the  critical  realist 
stresses.  And  he  believes  that  a  cognitive  grasping  by  means 
of  characters  or  universals  is  valid,  that  it  is  what  we  do,  and 
that  it  is  the  only  thing  we  can  do.  In  other  words,  his 
position  is  a  flat  challenging  of  the  dogma  that  knowledge 
must  be  a  presentation  of  the  thing  itself. 

While  we  are  analysing  knowledge  and  pointing  out  the 
difference  between  Lockianism  and  critical  realism,  another 
fact  needs  emphasis.  There  is  not  in  the  immediate  know- 
ledge-claim the  absurd  attempt  to  compare  idea  and  object. 
I  do  not  find  in  the  knowledge-claim  anything  but  predications 
about  the  thing  which  is  the  object  of  reference  or,  at  the 
level  of  perception,  assignment  of  characters  to  the  thing. 
And  yet  this  comparison  notion  was  one  absurdity  for  which 
non-presentative  realism  was  discarded  in  that  dogmatic  and 
blind  way  that  is  so  common  that  it  will  be  hard  to  get  a  fair 
hearing  for  critical  realism.  The  mistake  of  Locke,  who  had 
not  really  analysed  the  knowledge-claim  (note  his  definition 
of  knowledge  as  the  perception  of  the  agreement  or  disagree- 
ment of  two  ideas),  was  fastened  on,  to  the  exclusion  of  other 
possibilities.  If  we  had  both  a  cognitive  idea  and  thing, 
what  would  be  the  use  of  the  idea  ?  And  it  must  be 
remembered  that  a  cognitive  idea  as  a  part  of  a  knowledge- 
claim  is  quite  different  from  a  mere  image  as  an  object  of 
attention. 

The  act  of  knowledge  is  a  distinct  claim  or  assertion  which 
contains  an  idea  or  complex  of  universals  as  the  content  of 
its  assertion,  as  what  is  predicated  of  the  object  as  that 
object's  character.  Such  a  claim  has  its  postulate  and  its 
more  or  less  instinctive  basis.  Its  postulate — justified,  I 
think,  by  the  situation  of  the  percipient  organism  and  the 
guiding  value  of  knowledge — is  twofold :  (1)  the  revealing 
capacity  of  the  presentational  complex  with  its  differential 
pattern  and  (2)  the  ability  of  the  mind  to  elicit  by  thought 
the  maximum  of  knowledge  from  this  complex.  The  mind 
discovers  and  quarries  knowledge  out  of  the  material  of 
perceptual  observation. 

What  can  be  revealed  by  the  presentational  complex? 
Let  me  stress  the  fact  that  much  of  the  objection  to  non- 
presentative  realism  lay  here.  My  answer  will  at  least  be 
definite,  and,  I  think,  true.  That  will  be  revealed  which  cm 
be  reproduced.  And  the  more  that  I  reflect  and  the  more  I 
study  science,  the  more  I  am  convinced  that  it  is  the  deter- 
minate order,  structure  and  behaviour  of  the  physical  world 


36  ROY  WOOD   SELLARS  : 

which  is  reproduced.  It  is  a  correspondence  of  static  and 
dynamic  pattern  in  different  media  to  the  discovery  of  which 
all  sense-data  and  activities,  like  measurement,  can  act  as 
clues.  We  do  not  have  here  the  idea  of  entitative  likeness 
of  stuff  against  which  Berkeley  protested  when  he  said  that 
a  sensation  could  be  like  only  a  sensation,  a  view  which 
was  inherent  in  the  scholastic  conception  of  properties  in 
a  substratum.  What  we  know,  what  is  revealed,  is  the  deter- 
minate structure  and  behaviour  of  things  and  not  attributes 
in  the  old  sense,  whether  primary  or  secondary.  Thus  our 
theory  of  knowledge  agrees  with  Whitehead's  rejection  of 
the  old  substratum  notion  of  matter  while  yet  making  all 
sense-objects  subjective  together,  that  is,  in  the  situation  of 
the  percipient  event,  the  organism.  This  is  only  a  brief 
indication  of  the  entire  reinterpretation  of  what  knowledge 
grasps  and  what  is  reproducible.  It  is  the  pattern  of  things 
which  is  reproducible  in  experience,  just  as  the  structure  of 
an  organ  is  reproduced  by  the  histologist  in  wax.  The 
analogy  is  real,  though  the  difference  of  medium  must  not 
be  overlooked. 

My  conception  has  been  so  inadequately  grasped  in  the 
past — largely  my  own  fault,  I  have  no  doubt — that  I  wish  to 
be  certain  that  I  have  at  least  made  myself  clear.  My 
fundamental  concept  is  that  there  is  between  idea  and  thing 
an  identity  of  order  and  not  of  material.  A  thing  is  an 
ordered  material,  and  it  is  this  order  which  may  arise  else- 
where under  its  control  with  no  identity  of  material.  It  is 
a  correspondence  of  pattern  and  not  a  likeness  of  stuff  which 
I  have  in  mind.  The  difference  between  the  old  represent- 
ative theory  and  my  own  can  be  indicated  as  follows  : 

X     Substratum  f    I      i      i     j 

I— 4" — /     /     /     Patterned  thing 
A      B      C      D    Primary  qualities         L  J    I     I     I 

\  '  •  '  f       I         /"™^™/^^"^r 

resemble  I   I    I      I     I  (identity  of 

a        I      'c      d         Ideas  r~l — J     I     I      pattern) 

/     /     /     I J    Patterned  idea 

/     /     /     /    / 

From  this  contrast,  which  could  be  still  further  developed 
by  bringing  out  behaviour  as  the  temporal  phase  of  pattern, 
the  marked  difference  in  the  conception  of  what  knowledge 


CONCEKNING-  "  TKANSCENDENCE  "  AND  "BIFURCATION".   37 

grasps  comes  out.  We  cannot  grasp  the  stuff  of  our  object 
but  only  its  form  or  pattern ;  for  the  one  can  be  reproduced 
in  the  medium  of  experience,  the  other  cannot,  for  it  is  the 
existence  of  the  thing.  But  I  must  not  move  too  far  into 
my  metaphysics. 

Faulty  as  Locke's  epistemology  was,  the  nominalistic 
psychology  which  succeeded  it  was  still  worse.  Justice  was 
not  done  to  thought,  to  distinctions  and  to  cognitive  refer- 
ences. And  the  harm  was  done.  It  was  not  until  practically 
the  twentieth  century  that  realism  again  raised  its  head. 
And  then  nai've  realism  rather  than  the  more  subtle  critical 
realism  was  path-breaking. 

But  we  must  press  on  to  defend  transcendence,  a  notion 
which,  as  we  saw,  distinguishes  the  critical  realist  from  all 
other  schools  of  philosophy.  First  of  all,  let  us  point  out  that 
the  term  "  object  "  is  ambiguous.  When  Whitehead  states 
that  nature  is  what  we  are  aware  of  in  perception,  he  is  both 
right  and  wrong.  The  terms  "what"  and  "  aware"  need 
analysis.  In  perception,  reflexion  forces  us  to  make  dis- 
tinctions which  make  explicit  what  is  already  implicit. 
"  What "  breaks  up  into  object  and  its  content  or  appearance  ; 
"  aware  "  breaks  up  into  reference  and  consciousness  of  datum 
or  appearance.  Thus  the  critical  realist  is  quite  willing  to 
say  that  nature  is  what  he  is  aware  of;  but  he  holds  the 
situation  to  be  more  complex  than  does  the  nai've  realist. 
Let  us  call  the  datum  the  object  of  intuition  or  what  is  given 
(no  mystical  idea  of  intuition  is  assumed),  and  the  physical 
existent  the  object  of  perception,  the  thing  to  which  the 
organism  is  responding  and  adjusting  itself.  The  point  is 
that,  in  perception,  this  external  object  of  selective  behaviour 
is  affirmed  and  automatically  interpreted  in  terms  of  the 
datum  or  object  of  intuition.  It  is  this  apparent  coalescence 
or  identity  of  object  of  intuition  and  object  of  organic  ad- 
justment which  furnishes  the  unanalysed  point  of  departure 
and  strength  of  na'ive  realism. 

Because  of  this  identification  of  object  of  intuition  and 
object  of  adjustment,  without  which  consciousness  could 
have  no  guiding  value,  philosophy  has  assumed  that  an 
object  must  be  given  in  experience.  But  the  truth  is  that 
only  the  datum,  or  object  of  intuition  is  given.  The  auto- 
matic coalescence  or  identification  of  the  two  kinds  of  objects 
has  misled  philosophy.  A  physical  thing  is  an  object  only  in 
the  sense  that  it  is  made  an  object  by  the  percipient  organism. 
That  is  what  object  means  in  this  case.  By  its  very  nature 
and  situation  it  is  outside  the  individual's  experience-complex, 
though  not  outside  the  reach  of  knowledge  as  a  claim  or 


38  ROY  WOOD   SELLABS  : 

reference.  The  object  of  intuition,  the  datum,  the  appearance 
is  within  experience.  Once  this  distinction  is  thoroughly 
grasped,  it  will  be  seen  that  there  is  no  contradiction  in  the 
thought  of  a  transcendent  object.  The  object  of  the  per- 
cipient organism  is  by  its  very  nature  transcendent,  that  is, 
other  than  the  organism.  Perception  is  the  natural  identifi- 
cation of  object  of  intuition  and  object  of  response,  or  the 
assignment  of  the  one  object  to  the  other.  Is  the  critical 
realist  making  a  new  and  more  adequate  analysis  here  than 
has  been  done  in  the  past  ?  I  am  persuaded  that  he  is. 

The  existent  which  is  selected  as  the  object  of  reference 
has  its  own  determinate  nature.  It  is  a  patterned  or  ordered 
stuff.  What  character  has  the  cognitive  idea  to  enable  it  to 
give  knowledge  of  the  object?  I  have  argued  that  there  is  a 
reproduced  identity  of  pattern  or  order  in  the  dimensions  of 
space  and  time.  There  is  thus  an  identity  between  cognitive 
idea  and  object,  an  identity  of  understood  pattern  with  the 
pattern  of  the  physical  existent.  Put  in  other  words,  the 
applicability  of  universals  to  the  object  is  validated  by  this 
identity.  Since  one  member  of  the  two  terms  is  a  complex 
of  logical  characters  or  meanings,  the  identity  itself  may  be 
spoken  of  as  a  logical  identity.  But  it  must  be  remembered 
that  the  object  is  reproduced  only  with  respect  to  its  deter- 
minations and  not  existentially.  To  know  a  thing  is  not  to 
have  the  thing  itself  with  its  energies  and  creative  activities 
in  the  mind.  Knowledge  is  as  near  to  the  thing  as  we  can 
get  and  is  very  valuable,  but  by  its  very  situation  and  nature 
falls  short  of  being. 

To  guard  against  misunderstanding,  I  would  emphasise 
the  fact  that  the  data  of  perception  assigned  so  automatically 
to  the  object  are  rather  the  material  for  critical  knowledge 
which  can  employ  all  of  it  as  the  point  of  departure  for 
mature  critical  judgment. 

When  I  assert  that  critical  realism  involves  epistemological 
dualism,  I  do  so  with  my  own  critical  notion  of  epistemo- 
logical dualism  in  mind.  In  the  act  of  knowledge,  the  ex- 
istence of  the  idea  is  disregarded,  only  its  content  is  held 
before  the  attention.  Yet  reflexion  must  admit  that  the 
idea  which  grasps  the  determinations  of  the  object  through 
identity  is  yet  existentially  distinct  from  the  object.  This 
existential  distinctness  forces  us  to  speak  of  correspondence, 
for  in  correspondence  we  have  the  two  elements  of  numerical 
difference  and  logical  identity.  But  let  us  remember  that  in 
knowledge  the  idea  means  the  object  and  does  not  linger  on 
itself.  We  say  that  a  thing  is  composed  of  cells,  is  of  a 
certain  size,  behaves  in  a  certain  way,  etc.  In  knowledge, 


there  is  no  bifurcation  and  yet  the  data  are  in  the  situation 
of  the  percipient  event. 

The  mistake  to  be  avoided  is  to  think  of  something  as  pass- 
ing back  and  forth  between  mind  and  thing.  Aristotelianism 
was  not  free  from  this  mistake.  There  was,  also,  in  Aris- 
totelianism a  tendency  to  metaphysical  dualism  between  form 
and  matter.  Both  of  these  mistakes  are  quite  unnecessary. 
Form  or  pattern  as  against  matter  is  a  part  within  the  whole 
or,  better  yet  because  more  complete,  a  logical  distinction 
and  not  an  ontological  entity.  Yet  because  of  its  historical 
associations  in  scholastic  philosophy,  I  am  inclined  to  fight 
shy  of  the  term  "  essence  ". 

While  I  have  in  this  paper  attacked  Prof.  Whitehead's 
epistemology,  I  am  no  friend  of  bifurcation  for  either  science 
or  metaphysics.  But  what,  on  an  incomplete  analysis,  may 
seem  to  involve  bifurcation  may  not  actually  do  so.  I  think 
that  I  have  pointed  out  enough  to  make  it  clear  that  none  of 
the  bifurcative  positions  he  attacks  is  identical  with  critical 
realism.  Prof.  Whitehead  extrudes  mind  from  nature  in  a 
very  hasty  fashion.  Practically  no  philosopher  on  this  side 
of  the  water,  be  he  pragmatist,  new  realist  or  critical  realist, 
would  assert  with  Prof.  Whitehead  that  action  upon  mind  is 
not  action  in  nature.  Mind  is  not  alien.  It  is  the  nervous 
system.  And  the  nature  known  in  perception  is  identical 
with  the  nature  which  is  one  condition  of  the  sense-objects 
by  means  of  which  we  know  it.  But  let  me  hasten  to  add 
that  with  the  aim  of  Prof.  Whitehead  I  have  nothing  but 
agreement.  The  task  of  science  is  correctly  put  as  the  dis- 
cussion of  "  the  relations  inter  se  of  things  known,  abstracted 
from  the  bare  fact  that  they  are  known ".  And  yet  a  philo- 
sophy of  nature  can  hardly  be  separated  from  an  epistemology. 
There  will  be  quirks  in  it  which  will  reflect  the  assumptions 
made. 


III.— DR.  WILDON  CARR  AND  LORD  HALDANE 
ON  SCIENTIFIC  RELATIVITY. 

BY  J.  E.  TURNEB. 

BOTH  Dr.  Carr  and  Lord  Haldane  appear  to  draw  far  too 
heavily  upon  the  scientific  theory  of  relativity  as  an  argument 
for  the  philosophic  principle.  In  this  respect  Einstein's 
recent  statement  that  "  there  was  nothing  specially,  certainly 
nothing  intentionally,  philosophical  about  it "  L  is  highly 
significant ;  for  it  is  extremely  improbable  that  its  philosophic 
bearings  should  always,  during  his  long  investigation,  have 
been  altogether  absent  from  his  mind ;  and,  further,  such 
speculative  suggestions  as  he  has  advanced  have  taken  a 
wholly  different  direction.2 

It  is  therefore,  I  think,  fundamentally  important  to  re- 
cognise that  the  scientific  theory  in  itself  has  at  bottom  very 
little  bearing  on  any  form  of  the  philosophic  principle  of 
relativity;  so  little  indeed  that  it  is  even  doubtful  that  it  "is 
only  an  illustration  of  its  application  to  a  special  subject,"3 
moderate  though  this  position  is  as  compared  with  other 
recent  interpretations.  For  the  scientific  theory  is  concerned, 
and  is  concerned  only,  with  certain  definitely  limited  aspects 
of  space  and  time — with  what  Einstein  has  called  "  an 
analysis  of  the  physical  conceptions  of  time  and  space  " 4— 
a  limitation  which  is,  of  course,  perfectly  legitimate  from  the 
scientific  standpoint,  but  which  must  none  the  less  be 
carefully  borne  in  mind  in  any  discussion  of  the  theory's 
philosophic  implications.  To  pass  from  these  "physical 
conceptions"  to  the  philosophical  aspects  of  time  and  space 
is  to  "  cross  the  Rubicon  "  ;  and  much  of  the  prevailing  con- 
fusion is  due  to  the  transition  being  undertaken  as  though  it 
were  of  no  significance,  so  that  what  is  true  of  the  scientific 
concepts  is  also  regarded  as  true  of  time  and  space  within 
philosophy.  Thus  while  Dr.  Carr  and  Lord  Haldane  refer 

1  JReport  of  lecture,  Nature,  16th  June,  1921,  p.  504. 

2  Cf.  below,  p.  45,  n.  3. 

3  Haldane,  The  Reign  of  Relativity,  p.  34.     Cf.  p.  39. 

4  The  Theory  of  Relativity,  p.  19.     Cf.  p.  23,  "a  definition  of  time  in 
physics  ".     (My  italics.) 


J.    E.   TUENEK  :    SCIENTIFIC   EELATIVITY.  41 

to  them  as  distinguishable,1  neither  appears  adequately  to 
recognise  the  crucial  importance  of  the  distinction. 

This  impression  is  confirmed,  I  think,  by  a  curiously  inter- 
esting passage  in  Einstein's  Theory  of  Relativity.  "  We 
entirely  shun,"  he  says,  "  the  vague  word  space,  of  which, 
we  must  honestly  acknowledge,  we  cannot  form  the  slightest 
conception,  and  we  replace  it  by  motion  relative  to  a  prac- 
tically rigid  body  of  reference."2  It  is  difficult  to  appreciate 
the  exact  value  of  this  statement,  because  it  is  not  strictly 
adhered  to  by  Einstein  himself  ; 3  it  seems  to  me  to  indicate 
his  emphasis  on  the  "  physical  interpretation  of  space  and 
time  data  "  (p.  79),  and  his  explicit  exclusion  of  any  wider 
reference  ; 4  which  again  warns  us  that  in  going  beyond  the 
scientific  field  of  enquiry  we  cannot  interpret  scientific  con- 
clusions without  further  analysis  and  qualification. 

It  is  in  consonance  with  this  that  Cunningham  maintains 
that  "  The  principle  is  not  a  metaphysical  doctrine  based  on 
the  supposition  that  it  is  impossible  to  conceive  of  an  absolute 
standard  of  position  in  space.  Dynamical  relativity  is  a 
different  thing  from  a  statement  as  to  what  is  within  the 
power  of  the  mind  to  conceive  about  position  and  motion."  5 
While  therefore  it  may  be  true,  it  is  irrelevant  to  the  bearing 
of  scientific  relativity  upon  philosophy  to  assert  that  "  the 
idea  of  an  absolute  motion  is  a  metaphysical  invention  of  the 
school  of  classical  mechanics,"  or  that  "  absolute  position, 
shape,  and  measurement  are  all  unmeaning  "  ; 6  for  in  so  far 
as  "  absolute  entities  "  (or  concepts)  are  criticised  by  Einstein 
they  are  regarded  not  as  metaphysically,  but  purely  as  physic- 
ally, "absolute";  the  "absolute  time,"  e.g.,  of  classical 
mechanics  is  ''absolute,"  not  metaphysically,  but  as  "inde- 
pendent of  the  position  and  the  condition  of  motion  of  the 

1  The  Reign  of  Relativity,  pp.  55,  59,  70.     The  Principle  of  Relativity, 
chaps,  i.  and  vii. 

2  P.  9.     My  italics. 

3  He  speaks,  e.g.,  of  "  relative  orientation  in  space  of  co-ordinate  systems  " 
(p.  32) ;    "  the  law  governing   the  gravitational  field  in  space "  (p.  64) ; 
again,    "space  is  a   three-dimensional    continuum"    (p.    55)    and   "the 
geometrical  properties  of  space  are  determined  by  matter"  (p.  113). 

4  Cf.,  "In  respect  of  its  role  in  the  equations  of  physics,  though  not 
with  regard  to  its  physical  significance,  time  is  equivalent  to  the  space- 
co-ordinates  (apart  from  the  relations  of  reality)"  ;    Nature,  17th  Feb., 
1921,  p.  783.     (Italics  mine.)     Similarly  Cunningham,   "Space  and  time 
co-ordinates  are  only  means  of  specifying  a  single  fact  or  occurrence  "  ; 
Relativity   and   the   Electron   Theory,    1st   ed.,    p.    73.     Einstein's  later 
remarks  seem  to  me  to  convey  a  suspicion  that  his  standpoint  has  been 
misinterpreted  philosophically. 

5  Op.  cit.,  pp.  2,  3. 

(!  The  Reign  of  Relativity,  pp.  55,  88. 


42  J.    E.   TUKNEE  : 

system  of  co-ordinates  "  ; l  here,  as  always,  we  are  concerned 
with  " physical  conceptions".  And  when  (further)  we  limit 
ourselves  to  these,  we  find  that  absolute  standards  can  never 
be  completely  dispensed  with,  inasmuch  as  the  Eigenzeit 
and  Eigenraum  of  any  given  reference  system  are  (for  that 
system)  absolute  and  invariant.2 

(1)  From  this  general  standpoint,  which  I  think  expresses 
Einstein's  meaning  in  saying  there  is  nothing  philosophical 
about  his  Theory,3  it  appears  to  me  that  throughout  Dr. 
Carr's  .volume  no  adequate  distinction  is  maintained  between 
space  and  time  on  the  one  hand  and  our  systems  of  measur- 
ing these  entities  on  the  other ;  we  are  carried  from  the  one 
to  the  other  without  any  sufficient  indication  of  the  vital 
importance  (for  Philosophy)  of  the  transition. 

The  Theory  that  the  results  of  observations  which  involve 
spatio-temporal  measurements  are  conditioned  by  the  velocity 
of  the  observer,4  involves  a  limiting  case  which  has  been  too 
much  disregarded  in  philosophic  discussion — the  instance,  i.e., 
of  observers  in  one  reference  system,  who  obtain,  therefore, 
identical  results.  This  identity  is  of  subordinate  importance 
to  scientists,  because  it  is  comparatively  free  from  mathe- 
matical difficulties ;  but  philosophically  it  is  extremely  signi- 
ficant, for  two  reasons.  First,  because  it  proves  quite 
definitely  that  those  discordances  in  the  content  of  our 
experience,  from  which  so  many  important  philosophic 
conclusions  have  recently  been  drawn,  are  due  to  nothing 
except  either  (a)  differences  in  the  velocities — not  of  the  ob- 
servers, as  conscious  observers,  but — of  their  physical  systems 
of  reference,  or  (&)  certain  conditions  (again  physical) 
whose  nature,  though  as  yet  far  from  being  understood, 
nevertheless  presents  aspects  which  have  abstract  mathe- 
matical equivalents.5 

These  discrepancies,  therefore,  while  they  certainly  affect 
most  materially  the  detailed  content  of  knowledge,  can  have 
no  bearing  whatever  on  the  nature  of  knowledge,  or  of  ex- 
perience, or  of  reality,  in  general  and  as  such  ;  unless,  i.e.,  we 
are  going  to  base  our  epistemology  on  the  rate  at  which  we 
happen  to  be  moving,  or  on  gravitational  potentials.  And 

1  The  Theory  of  Relativity,  p.  56.     Cf.  Dr.  Carr,  op.  cit.,  p.  20,  at  foot. 

2  Cf.,  "A  law  of  such  change  which  is  independent  of  such  relativity," 
Reign  of  Relativity,  p.  98. 

3  In  accordance  with  Einstein's  distinction  between  the  scientific  prin- 
ciple, and  the  scientific  theory  of  relativity  (The  Theory  o/  Relativity,  pp. 
19,  40)  I  shall  denote  these  by  capitals,  reserving  "principle"  for  philo- 
sophic and  general  usage. 

4  And  further  by  acceleration,  which  brings  in  gravitational  phenomena. 

5  Cf.  Dr.  Carr,  op.  cit.,  pp.  21-23. 


DK.   WILDON   CARR  AND   LORD  HALDANB   ON   RELATIVITY.       43 

the  second  reason  is  that  the  identity  in  question  constitutes 
what  (as  I  have  already  mentioned)  all  scientists  accept  as 
11  absolute  " — the  invariable  Eigenraumzeit  of  observers  with 
identical  velocity.1 

But  this  "  absolute  "  has  been  quite  unduly  neglected  in 
recent  philosophy,  perhaps  because  of  its  predilection  for  that 
form  of  original  sin  manifest  in  all  thought — its  relativity. 
It  is,  however,  at  least  as  important  as  the  variability  arising 
from  a  mere  physical  difference  in  velocity  or  in  gravitational 
field.  It  is  (further)  a  simple  logical  consequence  of  these 
premises  that  the  varying  results  can  be  exactly  correlated, 
and  the  formulae  of  one  observer  transformed  into  those  of 
another.  The  entire  situation  is  a  natural  (physical)  result 
of  the  finite  velocity  of  light,  allied  with  our  physiological  in- 
capacity to  receive  stimuli  more  basal  than  light  signals  are ; 2 
and  it  is  easy  to  conceive  conditions  which  would  altogether 
exclude  scientific  relativity.  This  would  be  the  case  if  gravi- 
tational impulses  have  infinite  velocity,3  and  if  we  could, 
through  a  special  sense-organ,  directly  perceive  changes  in 
gravitational  intensity. 

Quite  apart  therefore  from  Einstein's  or  Cunningham's 
assertions  to  the  contrary,  it  is  altogether  irrelevant  to  main- 
tain that  "  the  particular  concepts  with  which  the  principle 
[Theory]  of  relativity  deals — space,  time  and  movement — are 
metaphysical,  and  the  essential  concern  of  philosophy  ".* 
Obviously  we  have  here,  at  the  very  outset,  that  transition 
from  "physical  conceptions"  to  metaphysical  which  is,  I 
would  submit,  as  yet  unjustified  and  illegitimate.5  But  there 

1  Cf.,  "  The  absolute  in  Nature  is  not  abolished  by  the  "  Theory,  Nature, 
17th  Feb.,  1921,  p.  781.  Also  Prof.  Eddington  in  MIND,  April,  1920,  p. 
145,  and  Haldane,  "change  in  standpoint  gives  no  change  in  the  actual "  ; 
op.  cit.,  p.  402. 

2 1  may  be  psrmitted  to  refer  to  the  Journal  of  Philosophy,  14th  April, 
1921,  where  I  have  attempted  a  simplified  presentation  of  the  facts.  Cf.  also  : 
"  The  difficulties  and  paradoxes  associated  with  temporal  conceptions  arise 
from  the  finite  velocity  of  propagation  of  all  signals,"  Campbell,  Physics: 
The  Elements,  p.  552.  "We  have  not  taken  account  of  the  inaccuracy  in- 
volved by  the  finiteness  of  the  velocity  of  light,"  Einstein,  op.  cit.,  p.  10. 

3  This  point  is  at  the  moment,  I  think,  undecided. 

4  Principle  of  Relativity,  p.  v.     Cf.,  Prof.  Kddington — "World- wide  time 
s  a  mathematical  system  according  to  arbitrary  rules  ;    it  has  not  any 

structural — still  less  any  metaphysical — significance  "  ;  Nature,  loc.  cit., 
p.  804. 

5  As  this  point  is  fundamental  I  may  quote  Einstein's  own  account  of 
the  history  of  his  Theory.     "  The  entire  development  starts  off  from,  and 
is  dominated  by,  the  idea  of  Faraday  and  Maxwell,  according  to  which  all 
physical  processes  involve  a  continuity  of  action."      He  proceeds  to  trace 
the  enquiry  through  a  number  of  similarly  scientific  concepts  which  in- 
clude "the  physical  significance  of  space  and  time  "  and  "  the  assumption 


44  J.    E.    TUBNEE  : 

is  a  further  ground  for  the  charge  of  irrelevance.  Space, 
time  and  movement  are  not  the  only  concepts  that  are  meta- 
physical. Every  ultimate  concept  is  metaphysical ;  matter, 
energy,  life,  mind  e.g.,  in  science  alone ;  and  the  Theory  of 
relativity  has  no  more  (and  of  course  no  less)  connexion  with 
any  philosophic  conclusions  than  has,  e.g.,  the  quantum  theory 
of  energy  or  the  method  of  chromosome  division.  It  is  il- 
logical, if  not  actually  erroneous,  to  argue  that  because  the 
Theory  asserts  that  certain  results  based  on  spatio-temporal 
measurements  are  relative,  and  because  further  time  and 
space  are  metaphysical,  therefore  philosophic  relativity  is 
either  substantiated  or  disproved.  I  am  not  here  contending 
either  for,  or  against,  philosophic  relativity ;  I  merely  urge 
that  scientific  relativity  has  but  the  slightest  possible  bearing 
on  the  question.  Scientific  relativity  is  concerned  with 
purely  physical  conditions;  philosophic  relativity  with  the 
relation  between  mind  and  its  content,  or  between  mind  and 
reality,  within  which  of  course  space,  time  and  movement  are 
included.  But  if  it  be  argued  that  this  inclusion  furnishes  the 
required  connecting  link,  the  obvious  reply  is  that  philosophic 
relativity  is  not  limited  to  these,  but  applies  universally ; l  the 
Theory,  therefore,  restricted  as  it  is  to  physical  spatio-tem- 
poral concepts,  can  have  no  direct  bearing  on  the  general 
philosophic  problem.  It  no  more  follows  that  because  all 
such  concepts  are  physically  relative,  therefore  time  and 
space  are  philosophically  relative,  than  that  because  currency 
systems  are  all  relative,  therefore  value,  as  a  metaphysical 
concept,  is  also  relative.2 

(2)  Dr.  Carr  advances  other  conclusions  for  which  it  is 
extremely  difficult  to  find  any  basis  within  scientific  research 
itself.  He  regards  the  advance  from  the  special  to  the 
general  form  of  the  Theory  as  a  sufficient  ground  for  sub- 
jectivism. "  The  general  principle  [Theory]  is  acknowledged 
to  concern  the  most  fundamental  philosophical  concepts  of 
the  nature  of  the  universe.  The  essence  of  it  is  to  introduce 


that  simulbaneity  has  a  meaning  independent  of  the  state  of  motion  of  the 
system  of  co-ordinates  used  ".  Similarly  Cunningham  states  that  Newton's 
"  space  and  time  are  natural  products  of  Nature's  laboratory,  to  be  puri- 
fied, perhaps,  but  not  to  be  rejected  as  spurious  ".  Nature,  loc.  cit.,  pp. 
782,  785.  (My  italics.)  Cf.  Dr.  Carr,  op.  cit.,  p.  3,  on  "rejection  of  space 
and  time  ". 

1  This  is  the  fundamental  principle  of  Lord  Haldane's  volume. 

2  The  mathematicians  whose  work  lies  at  the  base  of  the  Theory  have 
duly  emphasised  the  essential  distinction  between  space  and  time,  and 
spatio-temporal  measurement  systems.    Cf.  Journal  of  Philosophy,  loc.  cit., 
pp.  214,  215.     Also  Mach,  Space  and  Geometry,  pp.  97,  98. 


DE.  WILDON  CAKR  AND  LORD  HALDANE  ON  RELATIVITY.   45 

subjectivism  into  physical  science."1  I  have  already  dealt 
with  the  character  of  the  concepts  here  concerned ;  but 
further,  both  the  general  and  the  special  Theories  rest  on  pre- 
cisely the  same  basis.  The  former  has  no  peculiar  connexion 
whatever  with  subjectivism  or  with  the  "  mind  of  the  ob- 
server ". 

The  special  Theory  deals  with  uniform  rectilinear  motion  ; 
the  general  with  rotational  and  accelerated — and  therefore, 
through  the  Principle  of  Equivalence,  with  gravitational — 
motion.2  But  in  what  possible  sense  can  this  theoretical  ex- 
pansion be  regarded  as  introducing  subjectivism  into  science  ? 
Accelerated  motion  is  no  more  subjective  than  is  uniform, 
nor  is  the  "  mind  of  the  observer  "  more  in  evidence  when 
gravitation  operates  than  when  it  does  not.  And  if  it  is 
argued  that  all  motion  is  subjective,  or  the  mind  always 
active,  the  reply  is  (once  again)  that  these  comprehensive 
statements  are  too  comprehensive,  and  are  quite  unaffected 
by  any  change  in  the  scope  of  the  Theory ;  their  truth  or 
falsity  rests  on  altogether  separate  grounds.  Even  such 
speculative  suggestions  as  Einstein  has  put  forward  have  not 
the  remotest  connexion  with  subjectivism,  but  are  strictly 
limited  to  physical  enquiries.3 

Thus  it  is  not  the  "mind  of  the  observer  "  that  is  directly 
concerned  by  either  form  of  the  Theory ;  it  is  merely  his 
velocity,  or  rather  the  velocity  (or  its  equivalent)  of  his 
reference-system.  Mind  is  not  active  in  any  unique  way  in 
relativity  investigation,  and  relativity  as  such  therefore  can 
confer  no  new  and  original  status  on  mind  which  it  does  not 
possess  already.  I  consider  this  point  further  in  connexion 
with  co-ordination,  passing  meanwhile  to  the  "independence  " 
of  observations. 

"It  is  impossible,"  continues  Dr.  Carr,  "to  abstract  from 
the  mind  of  the  observer  and  treat  his  observations  as  them- 
selves absolute  and  independent  in  their  objectivity  "  ; 4  thus 
positing  a  relation  between  observations  and  the  mind,  the 

1  Op.  cit.,  p.  21.     Cf.t  p.  20,  "  introduction  .  .  .  of  a  subjective  element ". 

2  "  Einstein  asks  us  to  consider  the  result  of  supposing  that  the  dis- 
tinction between  centrifugal  force  and  gravitational  is  not  essential  .   .   . 
his  principle  of  equivalence  "  (Cunningham,  Nature,   llth  Dec.,   1919, 
p.  374).     "The  general  form  of  relativity  is  founded  on  the  equality  of 
inertial  and  gravitational  mass "   (Brose,   Theory  of  Relativity,  p.   21). 
"  Can  gravitation  and  inertia  be  identical  ?     This  question  leads  directly 
to  the  General  Theory"  (Einstein,  Nature,  17th  Feb.,  1921,  p.  783). 

3  "Is  the  spatial  extent  of  the  universe  finite  ?    Is  inertia  to  be  traced 
to  mutual  action  with  distant  masses  ? "  are  questions  to  be  decided  by 
"a  dynamical  investigation  of  fixed  stars  "  ;    Nature,  loc.  cit.,  p.  784. 

4  Op.  cit.,  p.  21. 


46  J.    E.    TURNER  : 

character  of  which  has  now  been  finally  determined  by  the 
Theory.  But  just  as  we  have  seen  that  the  "  absoluteness" 
of  time  repudiated  by  the  Theory  is  a  purely  physical 
characteristic,  so  here  the  independence  that  is  denied  sub- 
sists in  no  sense  as  between  the  mind  and  observations,  but 
rather — again  a  radically  different  matter — between  our 
scales  and  units  and  the  observed  phenomena. 

"  The  whole  relativity  doctrine  asserts  that  the  measure 
relations  of  the  phenomena  perceived  are  incapable  of  deter- 
mination on  any  absolute  scale,  independent  of  the  pheno- 
mena themselves.  The  gravitational  field  must  be  included, 
and  must  affect  the  measure  relations  in  every  physical 
aspect  "  ; l  or  as  Dr.  Carr  himself  expresses  this,  but  without 
noting  its  fundamental  implications,  "  it  requires  us  to  give 
up  the  assumption  of  an  absolute  standard  of  reference  for 
the  measurement  of  the  velocity  of  a  system  ",2  It  is  there- 
fore always  the  phenomena  and  the  scales  that  are  here 
interdependent  and  relative — not  mind  and  its  observations 
in  any  direct  and  unique  sense  characteristic  of  physical 
relativity  but  absent  in  other  cases. 

(3)  This  consideration  applies  to  some  degree  to  Dr.  Carr's 
later  elucidation  of  his  general  position  in  Nature*  There 
we  find  that  the  reference  to  mind,  which  he  regards  as 
finally  substantiated  by  relativity,  takes  the  form  not  (it  is 
needless  to  say)  of  any  crude  subjectivism,  but  of  "  a  power 
inherent  in  the  monads  to  co-ordinate  ever-varying  points  of 
view.  By  monads  I  mean  minds  as  metaphysical  reals." 
And,  while,  with  Dr.  Carr,  mind  is  for  myself  one — if  not  the 
sole — clue  to  the  nature  of  Keality,  both  as  being  the  highest 
concrete  real  of  which  we  have  direct  experience,  and  in 
virtue  of  what  its  actuality  transcendentally  implies,  still  I 
fail  to  see  that  this  belief  derives  any  support  from  the 
results  of  the  relativity  Theory.  The  co-ordinating  activity 
of  mind  remains  what  it  was  before ;  it  is  merely  the  co- 
ordinated material  that  is  different,  together,  of  course,  with 
the  formula  that  make  possible  the  higher  accuracy  of  the 
co-ordination.  If  we  survey  the  whole  of  the  subject  matter, 
this  seems  to  me  to  be  obvious.  Gravitation,  spectral 
phenomena,  planetary  motion,  electronic  vibration — these 
have  all  been  already  co-ordinated,  and  most  efficiently  co- 
ordinated, by  the  human  mind  in  virtue  of  its  "  inherent 
power,"  whether  that  implies  monadism  or  not.  And  now 
this  same  "inherent  power"  is  supplied  with  fundamentally 

1  Cunningham,  with  reference  to  Riemann,  Nature,  17th  Feb.,  1921, 
p.  786. 

2  Op.  cit.,  p.  22.     My  italics.  *  Loc.  cit.,  p.  810. 


DR.  WILDON  CARR  AND  LOBD  HALDANE  ON  EELATIVITT.   47 

new  data ;  with  new  assumptions  as  to  the  velocity  of  light 
and  the  possibilities  of  interpreting  gravitational  phenomena 1 
and  geometrical  principles.  But,  epoch-making  as  this  ad- 
vance undoubtedly  is,  it  in  no  way  concerns  the  status  of 
mind  in  its  advance  to  reality ;  it  merely  corrects — funda- 
mentally of  course — the  details  of  that  conceptual  content 
which  enables  mind  to  apprehend  objective  reality. 

(4)  These  considerations  apply  also  to  Lord  Haldane's  treat- 
ment of  the  question,  in  spite  of  his  explicit  exclusion  of  all 
subjectivism.  Even  on  this  important  point  his  position,  so 
far  as  his  brief  references  go,  is  somewhat  obscure.  Analysis 
of  his  epistemology  would  show,  I  think,  that  his  objectivism 
is  by  no  means  firmly  based.  "Perception,"  he  asserts,  "  is  in 
itself  chaotic  and  formless.  It  is  only  by  interpretation  that 
we  recognise.  .  .  .  Into  the  results  apparently  yielded  by 
direct  sense-awareness  concepts  have  entered  with  trans- 
forming power."2  But  what  is  perception  itself  except 
"interpretation"? — an  "interpretation,"  further,  which  is 
the  result  of  the  transformation  of  "  direct  sense-awareness  " 
by  means  of  concepts.  Lord  Haldane  almost  seems  to  posit 
two  independent  agencies,  "  sense-awareness "  or  "  sensa- 
tions,"3 and  concepts — the  latter  acting  on  the  former  like 

1  This  particular  point,  though  of  subsidiary  importance  as  within  the 
whole  investigation,  seems  to  me  to  have  been  more  radically  misunder- 
stood than  any  other.  I  can  see  no  grounds  for  the  widespread  opinion 
that  Einstein  has  explained — in  any  final  sens; — gravitation;  much  less, 
of  course,  explained  it  away;  and  this  applies  to  "forces"  in  general. 
"  Einstein's  theory,  though  it  helps  us  to  discover  the  laws  according  to 
which  phenomena  occur,  cannot  lay  claim  to  provide  a  mechanical  ex- 
planation of  them "  (Nature,  31st  March,  1921,  p.  134) ;  it  is,  in  brief, 
descriptive  rather  than  explanatory,  although  a  precise  description  of 
phenomena  has,  of  course,  the  highest  possible  value.  The  calculation  of 
planetary  motion  is  more  accurate  ;  kinematical.y,  gravitational  motions 
may  be  regarded  as  accelerations  ;  and  gravitation  energy  and  inertia 
may  become  in  the  end  identified.  On  this  point  Dr.  Carr  seems  to  me 
to  be  somewhat  misleading.  He  speaks  (p.  11)  of  "contradictory  de- 
scriptions of  movement "  ;  but  the  descriptions  are  not  necessarily  con- 
tradictory ;  they  are  merely  alternatives,  one  of  which  is,  for  certain 
limited  purposes,  preferable  to  the  other.  But  there  still  remain  "  the 
energy  tensor  of  matter  "  (Einstein)  and  "world-mass"  (Weyl)  ; — reals, 
i.e.,  that  are  non-mental,  and  therefore  not  the  product  of  the  "power 
inherent  in  the  monads  to  co-ordinate"  (Carr).  Philosophy,  then,  is 
not  yet  committed  to  subjectivism,  and  the  "objectivity  of  the  universe " 
is  still  something  other  than  "  the  perception-actions  of  infinite  individual 
creative  centres  in  mutual  relation"  (Carr,  p.  162). 

3  Op.  cit.,  pp.  40,  119. 

3  Cf.  pp.  41,  46,  152  on  "sensations,"  "direct  sensation,"  "isolated 
impressions".  I  think  no  serious  theory  of  knowledge  sets  off  from  these. 
Lord  Haldane's  general  position  here  is  curiously  similar  to  Croce's 
throughout  his  Logic. 


48  J.  E.  TUKNEE: 

an  acid  on  a  base ;  whereas  the  truth  seems  to  be  that  some 
degree  of  "  interpretation  "  is  present  from  the  very  beginning 
of  experience — a  conclusion,  further,  more  in  consonance 
with  his  volume  as  a  whole.1  If,  again,  "our  world  begins 
in  sentience.  We  distinguish  our  sensations  in  relations 
of  time  and  space.  Object  and  subject  are  phases  within  a 
mental  process,"  2  we  approach,  to  say  the  least,  perilously 
near  to  a  subjectivism  whose  barriers  no  transforming 
concepts  whatever  will  surmount.  "I  cannot  get  beyond 
my  own  senses  in  immediate  apprehension,"  affirms  Lord 
Haldane ; 3  always  the  crucial  test  of  an  epistemology  is  its 
treatment  of  perception ;  a  subject  to  which  I  shall  return  in 
connexion  with  observation  and  experiment. 

This  however  is  not  the  main  issue,  which  concerns  the 
bearing  of  scientific  upon  philosophical  relativity.  I  think 
we  find  Lord  Haldane's  fundamental  argument  expressed  in 
the  statements :  "  Space  and  time  disappear  as  self-subsistent, 
and  in  their  place  we  get  a  plurality  of  relative  systems. 
(Einstein  claims)  to  have  deprived  space  and  time  of  their 
supposed  characters  as  self-subsistent  and  uniform  frame- 
works of  existence,  belonging  to  an  altogether  non-mental 
world.  Spatial  and  temporal  relations  depend  on  the  situa- 
tions and  conditions  of  observers.  The  character  of  space 
and  time  is  therefore  purely  relative,  and  so  is  their  reality."  4 

It  appears  to  me  that  Lord  Haldane's  "  therefore"  here  is 
highly  questionable,  and  that  it  is  neither  put  forward  by 
Einstein  himself  nor  established  by  Lord  Haldane.  If  we 
remember  that  time  and  space  are  for  Einstein  "physical 
conceptions" — that  time  is  for  him  "time  interval"  and 
space  "  space  interval  (distance)  " 5  while  the  "  situations  and 
conditions  "  are  throughout  also  physical — and  if  also  time 
and  space  are  given  their  fuller  philosophic  significance,6  it  is 
obvious  that  this  "therefore"  is  merely  taken  for  granted. 
We  cannot  pass  thus  directly  from  Einstein's  physical  con- 
cepts to  time  and  space  in  any  philosophical  sense  ;  and  the 
philosophic  principle  which  Lord  Haldane's  volume  through- 
out maintains  is  true  or  false  wholly  independently  of  the 
results  of  scientific  relativity. 

1  Cf.  p.  155  on  thought  and  feeling.  2  Ibid.,  pp.  158,  197. 

3  Op.  cit.t  p.  155.  4  Ibid.,  pp.  39,  83,  88. 

5  Theory  of  Relativity,  p.  30.     Cf.  p.  28,  "  relativity  of  conception  of 
distance  ". 

6  Unless  this  is  done  Lord  Haldane's  chapters  sink  into  a  mere  epitome 
of  Einstein,  instead  of  an  interpretation.     This  wider  significance  again  is 
placed  beyond  doubt  by  the  passage  just  quoted — •"  we  distinguish  sensa- 
tions in  relations  of  time  and  space" — which  cannot,  at  that  level,  be 
"  physical  conceptions  ". 


DK.  WILDON  CARR  AND  LORD  HALDANE  ON  RELATIVITY.   49 

For  what  is  the  essential  issue  here?  It  is  that  reality 
must  become  known  under  concepts — that  knowledge,  or 
experience,  or  mind,  is  " f oundational  of  reality";  and  I  fail 
to  see  that  scientific  relativity  has  the  slightest  bearing  upon 
this  principle.  For  it  is  not  concerned  with  categories  as 
categories ;  it  introduces  no  new  ones  and  it  dispenses  with 
none  of  our  earlier  ones ; l  it  merely  accepts  the  basal 
categories  of  space  and  time  and  then  renders  more  precise 
their  application  to  natural  phenomena — corrects  our  measure- 
ments of  time  and  space  intervals,  our  estimates  of  mass  and 
energy.  If,  at  the  outset  of  experience,  "sensations  present 
themselves  as  we  distinguish  them,  in  relations  of  time  and 
space,"  then  science,  for  its  more  special  and  limited  purposes, 
must  presuppose  them;  but  its  increased  accuracy  in  the 
employment  of  its  fundamental  categories  is  altogether  in- 
dependent of  their  nature  and  validity  as  categories.  Apart 
from  its  refinement  and  exactitude  scientific  relativity  has  in 
this  respect  no  more  philosophical  importance  than  had — to 
choose  an  extreme  but  emphatic  instance — the  transition 
from  the  moons  of  our  ancestors  to  our  calendar  months. 

(5)  The  fallacy  of  any  identification  of  time  and  space, 
philosophically  considered,  with  "physical  conceptions  "  be- 
comes further  apparent  if  we  view  the  question  from  a 
different  angle.  This  term,  from  the  scientific  standpoint, 
is  perfectly  justifiable,  since  science  is  in  the  main  concerned 
with  concepts.  But  if  we  take  this  to  be  unqualifiedly  true, 
and  if  we  proceed  to  argue  that  space  and  time  are  solely 
concepts,  then  our  philosophy  must  (in  this  respect  at  least) 
become  a  merely  conceptual  Idealism — a  "  ballet  of  bloodless 
categories  ".  Science  is  preserved  from  this  by  its  inseverable 
connexion  with  perception.  "  The  concept  (simultaneous)" 
remarks  Einstein,  "  does  not  exist  for  the  physicist  until  he 
has  the  possibility  of  discovering  whether  or  not  it  is  fulfilled 
in  an  actual  case  ...  he  can  decide  by  experiment  .  .  ." ' 
Upon  this  underlying  perceptual  basis  concepts  may  be  reared 
as  high  as  we  choose,  even  until  time  and  space  are  wholly 
dispensed  with ; 3  but  they  must,  in  some  way  or  other,  be 
included  within  our  original  content.  This  indispensable 

1  Unless  every  fresh  mathematical  refinement  is  a  "category". 

2  Theory  of  Relativity,  p.  22.     Cf.t  "The  introduction  of  mathematical 
conceptions  must  be  postponed  as  long  as  possible.     Integration  leads  to 
physically  significant  results  only  because  it  corresponds  step  by  step  to 
some  physical  process  "  (Campbell,  Physics :  The  Elements,  pp.  422,  523  ; 
also  Nature,  17th  Feb.,  1921,  p.  804). 

8 ' '  This  arrangement  does  not  even  need  to  be  such  that  we  must  regard 
xlt  x2,  x3  as  space  co-ordinates  and  x4  as  a  time  co-ordinate"  (Einstein 
ibid.,  p.  94.  Cf.  Reign  of  Relativity,  pp.  96,  97.) 

4 


50  J.   E.    TURNEE  : 

condition  seems  to  be  completely  ignored  by  Lord  Haldane. 
Perception,  we  have  already  seen,  is  "  chaotic  and  formless  "  ; 
but  further,  "  physics  does  not  deal  with  bare  sensations,  but 
mainly  with  the  coincidences  of  events,  coincidences  which 
are  not  immediately  presented  in  experience  " .l  This  state- 
ment, as  it  stands,  directly  contradicts  the  very  basis  of  the 
Theory,  whose  primary  object  is  to  correlate  with  absolute 
accuracy  the  coincidences  immediately  presented  to  per- 
ception.2 

This  misinterpretation  of  the  role  of  perception  leads  in  the 
end  to  a  complete  inversion  of  the  structure  of  experience  or 
of  reality,  which  thus  becomes  a  pyramid  poised  upon  its 
apex.  I  have  quoted  already  the  passage  (p.  197),  "our 
world  begins  in  sentience.  Our  sensations  present  them- 
selves ...  in  relations  of  time  and  space."  But  elsewhere 
a  wholly  discrepant  account  of  the  development  of  knowledge 
is  given.3  Here  we  start  with  "  bare  awareness  of  change, 
in  which  space  and  time  have  not  yet  been  discriminated, 
the  activity  out  of  which  we  build  up  our  conceptions  of 
them.  We  approximate  to  intervals  neither  spatial  nor 
temporal  (which)  express  what  lies  at  the  foundation  on 
which  we  build  up  our  ideas  of  space  and  time  as  relations  " ; 
and  thus  "intervals,  neither  spatial  nor  temporal,"  intervene 
between  the  primal  sentience  and  the  later  spatio-temporal 
relations.  This  seems  to  be  a  direct  reversal  of  the  actual 
course  of  mathematical  procedure,  both  historically  and  logic- 
ally ;  for  this  starts  from  concrete  perceptual  experience, 
and  reaches  its  non-spatio-temporal  concepts  simply  by 
carrying  abstraction  farther  and  farther.  These  concepts, 
having  been  thus  attained,  certainly  constitute  a  basis  for 
further  construction.  But  to  regard  them  as  "the  founda- 
tion" from  which  "knowledge  is  rendered  at  a  later  stage 
particular,  by  observation  and  experiment"  (p.  98),  is  a 
completely  different  thing  ;  it  is  merely  to  reverse  the  process 
by  which  they  were  first  of  all  obtained.4  This  is  evident 
from  the  statement  (p.  98),  "the  characters  of  the  relations 
which  we  call  space  and  time  arise  from  the  movements  of 
bodies  changing  their  situations  .  .  ."  ;  for  these  aboriginal 

1  Reign  of  Relativity,  p.  47. 

2  "  Coincidence  is  the  only  exact  mode  of  observation  and  lies  ab  the 
bottom  of  all  physical  measurements  "  (Brose,  Theory  of  Relativity,  p.  14). 
But  in  this  connexion  it  seems  to  me  that  philosophy  cannot  altogether 
disregard  Einstein's  treatment  of  truth  (Theory  of  Relativity,  pp.  2,  124). 

3  P.  96.     Abridged,  but  I  think  not  distorted. 

4  Prof.  Eddington  also  seems  to  have  adopted  this  fallacious  method. 
Cf.  Journal  of  Philosophy,  21st  Oct.,  1920,  p.  609. 


DE.  WILDON  CAEK  AND  LOED  HALDANE  ON  EELATIVITY.   51 

"  movements,  bodies  and  situations  "  are  either  all  implicitly 
spatio-temporal  or  they  are  meaningless. 

(6)  An  analogous  misreading  of  the  character  of  mathema- 
tical abstraction  dominates  Lord  Haldane's  treatment  of 
gravitation  and  inertia,  and  leads  him  first  to  confuse  with 
one  another  two  distinct  principles  of  equivalence  —  (a)  of 
inertia  and  gravitation,  and  (6)  of  gravitational  and  accelerated 
motion  —  and  secondly  to  set  up  an  unfounded  contrast  be- 
tween Newton's  first  law  of  motion  and  Einstein's  law  of 
gravitation. 

The  Principle  of  Equivalence  proper  holds  true  in  itself  only 
as  a  purely  kinematical  abstraction  ;  it  expresses  an  equiva- 
lence (for  certain  purposes)  of  motions,  and  nothing  more  ; 
or  postulates  "  that  phenomena  in  a  field  of  gravitation  and 
in  a  field  produced  by  acceleration  of  the  observer"  are 
equivalent.1  It  certainly  does  not  justify  the  categorical 
statements  :  "of  force  physicists  know  nothing.  The  notion 
of  force  had  lost  meaning  for  physicists."  2  Such  a  view  is 
of  course  permissible,  but  it  is  not  incontestably  implied  by 
the  general  Theory,  except,  as  I  have  said,  as  a  kinematical 
abstraction. 

Dr.  Campbell,  e.g.,  denies  "that  force  is  properly  regarded 
as  a  derived  magnitude  at  all  ;  it  is  fundamental,  as  volume 
is  fundamental  "  ;  j  while  Einstein's  references  to  forces  are 
frequent.  Even  in  his  classical  illustration  of  "  the  man  in 
the  chest,"  a  "being  begins  pulling  at  this  with  a  constant 
force  "  ;  4  but  Lord  Haldane,  in  the  parallel  instance  on  page 
89,  ignores  both  the  "being"  and  the  force,  and  thus  loses 
sight  of  the  essentially  abstract  character  of  the  Principle, 
which,  with  the  indispensable  "if,"  is  clearly  presented  on 
page  57. 

But  when  we  turn  from  this  equivalence  between  gravita- 
tional and  accelerated  motion  to  the  equivalence  —  or  (perhaps 
better)  identity  —  of  gravitation  and  inertia,  quite  other  con- 
cepts are  involved.  To  be  strictly  accurate  we  should  speak, 
to  begin  with,  of  gravitational  and  inertial  mass  ;  and  mass, 
further,  as  interpreted  in  terms  of  energy.5  From  this  stand- 
point their  identity  can,  I  venture  to  think,  be  established  on 

1  Ecldington,  /Space,  Time,  and  Gravitation,  p.  212.  Like  all  other 
principles  it  has  of  course  important  implications. 


2  Reign  of  Relativity,  pp.  57,  89. 

3  Physics  :  The  Elements,  p.  392. 


4  Theory  of  Relativity,  pp.  51,  67,  80.     Nature,  17th  Feb.,  1921,  p.  783. 
Cf.  Weyl,  ibid.,  p.  801  :  "  pondero-motive  force  of   the  electro-  magnetic 
field  ". 

5  Einstein,  Nature,  ibid.     Brose,  op.  cit.,  p.  21.     Reign  of  Relativity, 
p.  57. 


52  J.  E.  TUENEE:  SCIENTIFIC  EELATIVITY. 

general  principles  quite  independently  of  scientific  relativity.1 
But  whatever  its  true  basis  may  be,  it  does  not  bring  Newton's 
law  into  conflict  with  Einstein's. 

In  the  first  place,  Lord  Haldane's  explication  of  inertia  is 
seriously  defective.  This  is,  I  think,  the  direct  result  of  his 
repudiation  of  force.  But  in  any  case  it  is  inaccurate  to  say 
that  "  a  body  remains  at  rest  or  goes  on  in  the  path  in  which 
it  is  moving  in  continuation  of  its  actual  motion  ".2  A  body 
remains  at  rest  only  when  no  force  acts  on  it.  I  grant  that 
we  do  not  understand  the  nature  of  force ;  but  that  the  state 
of  rest  here  involved  is  strictly  conditioned  cannot  thus  be 
ignored.  "Actual  motion"  again  is  continued  only  when 
rectilinear  and  uniform  and  (once  more)  under  the  action  of 
no  force.  So  that  it  is  meaningless  to  say  "  acceleration  .  .  . 
may  be  regarded  as  due  either  to  gravitation  or  to  inertia  ".3 
Given  a  force,  the  acceleration  is  determined  by  the  inertia, — 
a  case  wholly  different.  "  The  same  quality  of  a  body 
manifests  itself  according  to  circumstances  as  inertia  or  as 
weight";4  but  here  Lord  Haldane  has  left  the  "circum- 
stances "  out  of  account  altogether. 

Similarly  there  is  no  conflict,  such  as  seems  to  be  implied 
on  page  98,  between  Newton's  law  and  Einstein's.  Newton's 
law  holds  in  a  Galilean  domain,  wherein  "  isolated  material 
points  move  uniformly  and  in  straight  lines  "  ; 5  and  upon  it, 
as  a  foundation,  Newton  based  his  law  of  gravitation.  This 
now  proves  to  be  merely  approximate,  not  because  his  first 
law  is  not  true,  but  because  he  did  not  anticipate  that  "  al- 
most all  physical  quantities  are  functions  of  velocity,"  6  and 
that  therefore  mass  and  distance  vary  with  systems  of 
reference. 

All  this  implies,  finally,  that  what  philosophy  has  to  re- 
cognise in  scientific  relativity  is  simply  an  increased  degree 
of  accuracy  due  to  the  greater  exactitude  of  physical  concepts  ; 
which  means,  again,  that  little,  if  indeed  anything,  truly 
metaphysical  is  in  question  at  all.  The  established  conclu- 
sions of  the  Theory  will  contribute  to  the  future  Philosophy 
of  the  universe ;  but  this  involves  neither  a  complete  revolu- 
tion in  fundamental  concepts,  nor  any  substantial  advance  in 
the  Idealist  view  of  experience  and  knowledge.  "  Change  in 
standpoint,"  once  more,  "gives  no  change  in  the  actual  ". 

1  Mach  has  advanced  a  view  of  this  kind,  but  I  have  not  read  his  work. 

2  Reign  of  Relativity,  p.  89.  s  Ibid. 

4  Cf.  again  the  chest  illustration,  Theory  of  Relativity,  chap,  xx.,  and  p. 
65  ;  also  Reign  of  Relativity,  p.  57. 

5  Ibid.,  p.  100.  6  Richardson,  Electron  Theory  of  Matter,  p.  322, 


IV.— A  THEORY  OF  PERSONALITY. 

BY     WlNCENTY     LUTOSLAWSKI. 

I.  SELF  AND  PEESONALITY. 

MY  first  elementary  knowledge  of  myself,  when  I  began  to 
distinguish  myself  from  others,  was  the  ordinary  representa- 
tion of  a  body  moving  in  space,  and  animated  by  mind. 
Mind  and  body,  however,  were  not  yet  clearly  distinguished 
from  each  other,  and  activities  of  the  mind  were  credited  to 
the  body  or  to  its  parts,  as  when  we  speak  usually  of  a  feeling 
heart  or  of  a  thinking  brain.  Many  educated  persons,  and 
even  distinguished  thinkers,  if  their  thought  is  chiefly  directed 
towards  material  appearances,  have  no  deeper  knowledge  of 
themselves  than  children. 

Moral  pain,  the  habit  of  contemplation,  and,  to  a  certain 
extent,  also  the  study  of  the  history  of  human  thought  and 
action,  have  led  me,  like  many  others,  to  distinguish  more 
clearly  the  body  from  the  mind,  and  to  recognise  the  think- 
ing and  feeling  subject  from  within  as  a  spiritual  being,  as  a 
real  thing,  or  as  philosophers  say,  a  substance,  and  as  the 
first  original  model  of  every  conception  of  other  existing 
things. 

The  great  difficulty  of  expressing  in  any  foreign  language 
the  particular  conception  of  one's  own  reality  has  been  ex- 
perienced by  those  who,  writing  in  English  on  Sanskrit 
thought,  used  the  term  Atman,  as  having  another  meaning 
than  the  Self,  the  Ego,  the  spirit,  or  the  soul.  In  the  Polish 
language  we  have  the  peculiar  term  ja£n,  which  also  has  no 
exact  equivalent  in  English,  though  it  may  be  rendered  by 
Self.  Here  I  shall  use  the  term  Self  in  the  meaning  of  the 
Polish  term,  in  order  to  avoid  the  introduction  into  an  Eng- 
lish text  of  a  foreign  word  containing  two  letters  unknown  to 
the  English  alphabet.  But  this  Self,  as  I  understand  it,  is 
much  less  abstract  than  the  Self  of  English  writers  or  the 
Atman  of  Sanskrit  thinkers.  It  is  the  full  reality  of  a  con- 
scious subject,  with  all  his  thoughts,  feelings,  wishes,  and 


54  WINCENTT   LUTOSLAWSKi: 

perceptions.  All  these  contents  of  consciousness  are  events 
happening  in  me,  in  my  own  Self,  not  in  my  body,  though  I 
perceive  appearances  through  the  organs  of  my  senses,  and 
though  I  may  will  and  produce  external  events  in  the  material 
world  of  appearances,  perceived  through  the  senses.  I  remain 
myself  despite  all  the  variations  of  the  contents  of  my  con- 
sciousness. 

A  further  step  in  the  development  of  my  knowledge  of  my- 
self was  the  absolute  and  indestructible  certainty  of  the  inevi- 
table persistence  of  my  Self  after  the  dissolution  of  my  body. 
This  certainty  is  different  from  mere  beliefs  as  well  as  from 
inferences  obtained  by  discursive  reasoning.  Belief  in  im- 
mortality is  based  on  the  personal  testimony  of  those  who 
know  somehow  that  they  are  immortal.  This  knowledge  is 
not  similar  to  any  other  knowledge  of  facts  or  relations.  In 
my  experience,  as  in  the  spiritual  experience  of  many  others, 
it  has  been  a  sudden  revelation  (egatyvrjs,  Plato,  Symp.,  210e), 
coming  after  years  of  mere  thinking  on  this  matter,  and  of 
believing  the  testimony  of  others.  I  knew  at  that  time  (1885) 
most  of  the  arguments  for  immortality  advanced  by  thinkers 
and  believers.  But  they  did  not  then  appear  to  me  to  be 
definitively  convincing.  Suddenly  came  immediate  intuitive 
certainty,  with  the  evidence  of  mathematical  axioms,  and  it 
came  to  stay.  My  certainty  that  I  am  and  shall  be,  whatever 
happens  to  my  body  or  my  mind,  since  it  came,  has  never  dis- 
appeared for  a  single  moment,  neither  in  the  waking  state, 
nor  in  dreams,  neither  in  health,  nor  in  illness. 

I  know  from  books  that  this  sudden  discovery  of  the  ab- 
solute existence  of  one's  Self  as  a  Being  independent  of  the 
body  has  been  made  by  many  others.  If  it  is  genuine  it  leads 
to  a  permanent  and  continuous  consciousness  of  one's  inde- 
structibility. It  has  been  called  by  the  Polish  philosopher, 
Wroriski,  autocr Nation,  as  it  starts  a  new  relation  to  one's 
body  and  mind,  different  from  the  mental  attitude  of  the  vast 
majority  of  men  having  mere  beliefs,  or  endeavouring  to 
reach  a  knowledge  of  real  existence  by  reasoning. 

In  1894  I  had  a  conversation  on  this  subject  with  Prof. 
Henry  Sidgwick,  who  was  so  much  impressed  by  my  attitude, 
that  he  attempted  to  give  to  the  readers  of  MIND  (October, 
1894)  an  account  of  this  talk  (A  Dialogue  on  Time  and  Com- 
mon Sense).  But  he  admits  himself  that  when  he  tried  to 
write  down  this  talk  he  had  forgotten  too  much  of  it,  so  that 
he  had  to  allow  imagination  to  supplement  the  defects  of 
memory  "  trying  to  preserve  the  general  attitude  of  our  minds 
towards  each  other  ".  But  to  me  his  account  of  my  attitude 
proves  that  he  did  not  understand  me  at  all,  and  I  was  amazed 


A   THEORY  OF  PERSONALITY.  55 

at  the  possibility  of  such  a  complete  misunderstanding.1  If 
such  a  highly  intelligent  thinker  as  Henry  Sidgwick,  with 
his  wide  learning,  could  not  understand  a  very  common 
young  man,  full  of  his  discovery  of  concrete  real  existence, 
then  there  is  no  hope  of  a  general  recognition  of  this  experi- 
ence, limited  as  it  is  to  a  minority  of  psychologists  and  theo- 
logians. 

The  majority  of  my  readers  will  consider  my  discovery  as 
a  subjective  illusion.  But  a  persistent  illusion,  which  lasts 
throughout  life,  is  at  least  a  psychological  fact,  and  deserves 
the  attention  even  of  those  who  never  had  it.  There  is  a 
great  difference  between  the  mental  attitude  of  those  who 
have  such  an  absolute  and  lasting  certainty  of  their  own  ex- 
istence— (it  seems  to  have  been  reached  already  by  many  dis- 
ciples of  Pythagoras  and  Plato) — and  those  who  have  no 
such  certainty. 

However  rare  this  certainty  is,  it  is  not  yet  the  last  stage 
in  the  development  of  the  intuitive  knowledge  of  one's  Self. 
The  final  consecration  of  this  continuous  and  permanent  con- 
sciousness of  one's  real  existence  is  the  further  discovery  of 
our  pre-existence.  Pre-existence  does  not  follow  as  a  rational 
consequence  from  immortality.  Many  believers  in  immortality 
shrink  from  pre-existence  as  from  a  terrible  heresy.  Argu- 
ments in  favour  of  pre-existence  are  less  decisive  than  the 
usual  proofs  of  immortality.  There  is  a  widely  spread  preju- 
dice that  pre-existence  has  been  condemned  by  the  Roman 
Church,  and  the  great  majority  of  Catholic  priests  believe  in 
this  condemnation,  for  which,  however,  I  could  not  obtain 
any  proof  from  the  most  eminent  professors  of  the  Catholic 
universities  of  Louvain  and  Fribourg. 

For  me  the  subjective  certainty  of  pre-existence  is  parallel 
to  the  certainty  of  immortality,  and  it  is  not  a  conclusion 
from  any  line  of  argument.  I  know  that  I  have  existed  be- 
fore this  life,  either  on  earth  as  man,  or  elsewhere  in  similar 
conditions.  This  knowledge  is  for  me  not  less  evident  than 
any  mathematical  axiom,  and  needs  no  proof.  It  is  the 
foundation  for  many  other  convictions,  and  the  explanation 
of  many  difficulties  ;  it  does  not  contain  the  slightest  difficulty 
for  my  mind.  I  reached  this  certainty  later  than  the  certainty 
of  immortality,  but  since  I  reached  it,  more  than  thirty  years 
ago,  I  have  never  lost  it  for  a  single  moment.  And  so  far 
as  I  know  the  number  of  those  who  share  this  certainty  is 
rapidly  growing  on  earth.  All  the  great  Polish  poets  and 
thinkers  during  the  nineteenth  century  had  it :  Wroriski, 

1  He  did  not  even  understand  that  it  was  not  fair  to  call  a  Pole  ft 
Russian  professor  because  he  taught  at  a  Russian  university. 


56  WINCENTY   LUTOSLAWSTU: 

Cieszkowski,  Trentowski,  Towiariski,  Mickiewicz,  Krasiriski, 
Slowacki,  Goszczynski,  Wyspianski — to  mention  only  the 
greatest. 

My  eternal  existence  as  a  true  Self  has  its  experimental 
limitations  owing  to  my  close  connexion  with  a  body.  It  is 
not  certain  that  a  Self  must  always  be  incarnated  in  a  body, 
but  it  is  highly  probable  that  each  human  being  has  experi- 
enced many  incarnations.  The  incarnated  Self  lives  in  a  set 
of  conditions ;  and  personality  implies  the  sum  of  these  con- 
ditions. A  person  is  an  incarnated  Self  considered  in  all  its 
relations  to  the  external  world  and  to  its  own  past  and 
destiny.  A  person  owning  body  and  mind  depends  for  the 
conditions  of  its  existence  on  the  total  heredity  of  the  chosen 
body  and  on  the  acquired  experience  of  the  incarnated  Self. 
Whatever  I  have  ever  had  as  contents  of  my  consciousness 
may  be  under  certain  circumstances  recalled  to  my  memory ; 
and,  even  when  forgotten,  the  past  experience  of  my  Self  has 
an  influence  on  my  present  state  and  on  my  ability  to  feel, 
to  think  and  to  act  in  a  certain  way,  which  characterises  my 
individuality.  Thus  my  actual  condition  is  due  to  a  double 
line  of  influences :  the  succession  of  bodies  from  which 
descends  my  body,  and  the  succession  of  mental  states  which 
my  Self  has  experienced  in  past  incarnations. 

The  Self  is  not  by  itself  a  person  :  it  is  only  so  in  given  condi- 
tions of  dependence  on  a  part  of  the  external  world,  with  the 
possibility  of  influence  on  the  immediate  environment.  The 
person  has  therefore  not  the  same  permanent  identity  of 
substance  as  the  Self.  Each  Self  creates  by  incarnation  a 
succession  of  persons.  Even  within  one  incarnation,  despite 
the  continuity  of  one  and  the  same  body,  the  same  Self  can 
create  different  successive  persons,  like  an  actor  who  plays 
different  characters  on  the  stage  of  a  theatre.  Something  of 
this  kind  happens  in  real  life  whenever  an  act  of  will  or  an 
external  influence  causes  a  thorough  change  in  the  personal 
conditions.  Thus  a  girl  sometimes  completely  changes  her 
personality  by  marriage,  especially  if  she  marries  very  much 
above  her  rank,  or  if  she  gives  up  a  creative  original  activity 
in  order  to  devote  herself  to  her  husband  and  her  children. 
She  remains  the  same  Self,  but  many  personal  conditions, 
as  for  instance  name,  wealth  and  position,  are  changed. 

Not  all  the  personal  conditions  of  the  same  Self  can  be  thus 
changed  within  one  incarnation.  For  instance  we  cannot 
change  our  physical  sex,  nor  can  a  thoroughly  stupid  person 
become  clever  or  wise.  A  great  poet  like  Dante  or  Shakes- 
peare could  not  easily  become  a  truly  great  statesman,  though 
both  have  said  many  true  things  on  statesmanship.  We 


A  THEORY  OF   PERSONALITY.  57 

liave  seen  recently  an  eminent  Polish  musician  fail  completely 
when  he  attempted  to  rule  his  country  as  Poland's  Prime 
Minister.  Sometimes  the  same  man  succeeds  in  living  several 
different  lives  in  the  same  incarnation,  as  for  instance  a  gifted 
painter  who  during  the  war  became  a  famous  general. 

Personal  existence  has  a  variety  of  conditions  which  deter- 
mine the  activity  of  the  Self.  The  classification  and  defi- 
nition of  these  conditions  or  marks  of  personality  is  an 
important  problem  of  metaphysics,  and  if  we  wish  to  under- 
stand thoroughly  personal  existence  we  must  distinguish  what 
depends  on  the  essential  quality  of  the  Self  from  what  is 
given  to  that  Self  by  its  particular  place  in  space  and  time 
and  by  its  relations  to  other  Selves  and  persons.  A  com- 
plete characterisation  of  a  person  is  only  possible  if  we  are 
able  to  enumerate  all  the  conditions  or  relations  which  cause 
this  person  to  differ  from  all  other  persons.  Therefore  we 
have  to  ask  what  makes  human  beings  different  from  each 
other  and  how  many  kinds  of  human  existence  are  possible  ? 
'The  answer  to  this  question  will  lead  us  to  understand  the 
causes  which  determine  the  individual  destiny  of  each  Self 
in  each  incarnation  and  the  succession  of  different  persons 
animated  by  the  identical  Self. 

A  correct  classification  of  human  conditions  or  of  the  marks 
•of  human  personality  has,  besides  its  mataphysical  import- 
ance, also  moral  and  social  applications.  It  enables  us,  for 
instance,  to  judge  the  value  of  the  current  doctrine  of  class 
warfare.  Whether  workmen  and  capitalists  are  really 
different  classes  of  mankind  depends  on  what  principle  of 
classification  we  adopt  and  what  differences  we  consider  as 
the  most  important. 

The  conditions  of  personal  existence  depend  either  on  the 
Self  and  its  past  experience  or  on  the  body  and  its  inherit- 
ance. They  may  be  permanent,  as  for  instance  sex,  or 
variable  as  for  instance  age,  wealth,  and  health.  Some  of 
them  appear  to  be  innate,  as  for  instance  genius,  other  con- 
ditions seem  to  be  the  goal  of  many  efforts,  as  for  instance 
education,  or  moral  perfection. 

A  great  variety  of  opinions  is  possible  on  the  subject  of  the 
true  classification  of  men,  based  on  the  distinction  of  the 
real  conditions  or  marks  of  personality.  I  fail  to  find  in 
English  a  quite  convenient  term  to  design  these  qualities  or 
conditions  of  personal  existence  and  I  do  not  remember  any 
attempt  at  their  complete  enumeration,  definition,  and  classi- 
fication. Whenever  I  have  asked  anybody  in  how  many 
ways  a  human  being  may  differ  from  others  I  have  noticed 
:fchat  this  probJem  has  escaped  the  attention  of  the  students 


58  WINCENTY   LUTOSLAWSKI  : 

of  human  life.  If  I  am  mistaken,  I  shall  be  very  grateful  for 
the  indication  of  such  investigations.  My  own  classification 
of  sixteen  chief  marks  of  personality  will  be  the  final  outcome 
of  this  inquiry  into  the  meaning  which  each  particular  mark, 
condition  or  quality  has  for  individual  destiny. 

II.  SEX  AS  A  MAEK  OF  PEBSONALITY. 

The  most  obvious  difference  between  human  beings  con- 
sidered in  their  variety  is  the  difference  of  Sex;  the  first 
question  to  be  asked  about  a  person  whose  conditions  of  life 
we  wish  to  understand  thoroughly,  is  whether  it  is  a  man  or 
a  woman.  A  general  theory  of  personality  must  therefore 
explain  the  true  meaning  of  sex. 

At  first  sight  it  might  appear  that  the  whole  difference  of 
sex  depends  only  on  the  shape  and  function  of  the  organs  of 
reproduction.  Reproduction  being  one  of  the  many  functions 
of  life  and  not  inevitable  in  every  individual  life,  it  would  seem 
that  sexual  difference  is  not  essential,  as  many  human  beings 
live  without  ever  using  their  organs  of  reproduction  and  with- 
out even  being  aware  of  them.  When  I  pray  or  study,  I  seem 
to  be  simply  a  human  being,  neither  man  nor  woman.  The 
most  properly  human  activities  are  common  to  both  sexes. 
There  is  not  a  single  thought,  no  kind  of  emotion,  no  ideal  of 
human  activity,  which  could  not  be  common  to  persons  of  both 
sexes ;  and  every  possible  experience  of  one  sex  can  be  fully 
understood  and  assimilated  by  the  other  sex.  The  very 
existence  of  reproduction  can  be  entirely  forgotten  for  weeks, 
months,  and  years  by  those  who  are  engaged  in  intense  in- 
tellectual work  or  in  spiritual  contemplation  of  the  highest 
realities. 

From  such  a  point  of  view  the  sexual  difference  seems  to 
disappear,  or  to  be  of  the  same  secondary  importance  as  any 
other  purely  physical  difference — for  instance,  the  difference 
of  height  or  weight  or  muscular  strength.  For  certain  special 
purposes  all  these  differences  are  very  important,  but  they  are 
not  essential  in  the  sense  of  a  general  classification  of  the 
marks  of  human  personality.  Is  not  sex  also  such  a  difference, 
which  is  only  important  for  a  special  purpose,  that  of  repro- 
duction ?  We  may  ask  besides  whether  reproduction  has  to 
be  looked  upon  as  an  absolute  and  general  necessity  or  merely 
as  a  temporary  remedy  for  the  imperfection  and  decay  of  our 
bodies,  due  to  an  ancient  calamity  known  as  the  fall  of  man 
or  original  sin  in  our  religious  tradition  ? 

Such  questions  might  arise  if  we  limit  our  knowledge  of 
sex  to  the  facts  of  reproduction,  which  in  themselves  are  not 


A   THEOEY   OF   PERSONALITY.  59 

peculiarly  human,  as  there  is  such  a  close  analogy  between 
the  reproduction  of  human  beings  and  that  of  animals.  But 
outside  the  narrow  limits  of  biology  there  is  a  vast  field  of 
sexual  experience  which  is  properly  human  and  we  cannot 
fathom  the  mystery  of  sex  without  referring  to  that  wider 
spiritual  experience.  One  of  the  most  manly  men  in  human 
history,  Dante,  met  a  woman  a  few  times  in  his  life,  and 
described  his  experience  in  his  Vita  Nuova.  Much  later, 
towards  the  close  of  his  life,  in  the  ripest  and  greatest  of  his 
works,  he  still  considers  Beatrice  as  more  closely  related  to 
him  than  his  wife,  by  whom  he  had  several  children.  His 
marriage  appears  to  him,  when  he  speaks  to  the  world  at 
large  and  to  the  most  remote  posterity  in  his  immortal  poem, 
as  an  infidelity  against  his  first  love. 

This  contrast  between  the  spiritual  reality  of  love  and  the 
material  link  of  marriage  is  not  an  isolated  experience 
peculiar  to  the  great  Italian  poet.  It  permeates  the  whole 
of  human  life  and  literature  and  it  shows  that  sexual  ex- 
perience is  by  no  means  limited  to  the  facts  of  copulation 
and  reproduction. 

Moreover,  on  the  highest  plane  of  spiritual  life,  in  the 
mystic  experience  of  the  immediate  contact  of  men  and 
women  with  their  Creator,  again  the  sexual  difference  mani- 
fests its  power,  even  when  we  compare  the  confessions  of 
men  and  women  so  closely  related  to  each  other  as,  for 
instance,  Theresa  of  Avila  and  John  of  the  Cross.  Both 
being  equally  indifferent  to  physiological  reproduction  they 
still  remain  male  and  female,  and  every  page  written  by  one 
or  the  other  of  these  great  Carmelites  is  easily  recognised  as 
masculine  or  feminine.  Both  agree  with  Solomon  and  other 
mystics  in  their  habit  of  using  images  taken  from  sexual  love 
in  order  to  explain  their  mystic  experience  of  divine  love. 

If  we  look  at  the  widest  range  of  sexual  experience,  in- 
cluding not  only  what  has  found  an  expression  in  literature 
or  art,  but  also  the  infinite  variety  of  individual  destinies 
shaped  by  sexual  relations  or  impressions,  if  we  take  into 
consideration  that  there  are  many  other  sexual  relations 
than  the  intercourse  between  lovers  or  between  husband  and 
wife,  then  we  are  led  to  the  conclusion  that  sexual  onesided- 
ness  is  one  of  the  most  fundamental  limitations  of  Self,  con- 
stituting its  personality,  and  that  every  human  being  remains 
under  the  spell  of  this  strange  onesidedness  throughout  life, 
even  though  he  be  entirely  unaware  of  it. 

The  body  being  an  expression  of  the  soul,  a  symbol  of 
spiritual  reality,  the  bodily  sexual  difference  corresponds  to  a 
fundamental  spiritual  difference  and  cannot  be  limited  to  the 


60  WINCENTY  LTJTOSLAWSKI  : 

single  function  of  reproduction.  If  our  knowledge  of  the 
human  body  were  deeper,  even  a  single  hair  taken  from  any 
part  of  the  body  would  betray  the  sex  of  the  person  to  whom 
it  belonged.  The  difference  between  the  organs  of  repro- 
duction is  only  more  evident  and  known  because  we  have 
had  special  motives  to  study  it.  But  every  other  organ  in 
the  human  body  will  manifest  its  sexual  character  when 
physiological  investigation  has  gone  far  enough.  For  the 
present  we  are  unable  to  define  these  sexual  differences 
otherwise  than,  perhaps,  by  certain  averages  of  the  dimen- 
sions of  the  whole  body  and  its  parts.  Every  dimension  may 
be  found  in  both  sexes,  but  the  average  will  be  different  for 
each  sex. 

In  order  to  reach  a  definition  of  the  spiritual  aspect  of 
sexual  difference  we  have  first  to  decide  whether  we  consider 
this  difference  as  a  permanent  state  of  the  innermost  Self,  or 
as  only  a  condition  resulting  from  incarnation.  Am  I  a 
man  because  my  pre-existent  and  immortal  Self  received 
from  my  parents  a  masculine  body,  or  have  I  myself  built 
a  masculine  body  out  of  the  matter  furnished  by  my  parents, 
because  I  am  a  masculine  Self?  And  if  I  am  a  masculine 
Self,  is  this  masculinity  something  that  can  never  be  changed, 
or  only  a  passing  phase  of  my  spiritual  existence  ? 

Such  questions  are  not  likely  to  be  asked  by  everybody. 
Most  men  do  not  care  to  know  such  things  or  they  do  not 
admit  the  possibility  of  such  knowledge.  Most  of  us  have 
not  even  a  clear  reminiscence  of  onr  own  past  lives  and  it  is 
still  more  difficult  to  ascertain  the  past  lives  of  others.  With- 
out such  a  memory  how  could  we  pretend  to  know  the 
eternal  destiny  of  our  Selves  and  the  mystery  of  sexual 
differences  in  body  and  mind  ? 

We  must  here  follow  the  same  method  as  in  every  other 
investigation  of  reality.  Every  science  is  based  on  intuitive 
guesses  which  are  verified  by  some  kind  of  objective  experi- 
ence. Conformity  with  the  experience  of  our  senses  is  the 
test  of  physical  hypothesis.  But  there  is  a  vast  field  of 
spiritual  experience  not  less  evident  than  the  experience  of 
the  senses.  Dante's  love  of  Beatrice  was  to  him  a  fact  not 
less  than  the  colour  of  her  eyes,  though  everybody  could  see 
the  colour  of  those  eyes,  while  very  few  men  can  understand 
such  a  love  or  have  themselves  experienced  similar  feelings. 

It  is  true  that  only  very  few  human  beings  obtain  an 
absolute  certainty,  first,  of  their  immortality,  then  of  their 
pre-existence,  and  finally  of  their  sexual  destiny.  But  an 
intuitive  certainty  as  to  their  sexual  past  is  possible  for  those 
who  earnestly  strive  to  know  the  truth  about  themselves.  I 


A  THEOKY  OF   PERSONALITY.  61 

know  for  certain,  and  with  the  same  degree  of  unchanging 
certainty  as  I  know  of  my  immortality  and  pre-existence, 
that  my  actual  masculine  sex  is  not  imposed  upon  me  from 
without  by  the  conditions  of  my  conception  in  this  particular 
incarnation.  It  is  my  own  work  and  corresponds  to  a  pre- 
existent  state  of  my  own  Self,  which,  however,  was  not 
always  the  same ;  and  I  know  that  in  my  eternal  past  I  have 
experienced  both  sexes,  though  certainly  not  in  such  alter- 
nation that  after  each  masculine  life  a  feminine  life  should 
be  the  rule.  I  do  not  know  whether  I  need  ever  be  a  woman 
again,  but  I  am  certain  that  I  have  been  many  times  a 
woman.  There  is  nothing  in  the  life  of  woman  totally 
foreign  to  my  own  Self. 

Such  a  subjective  certainty  is  a  psychological  fact  which, 
as  the  testimony  of  a  single  individual,  might  be  a  personal 
illusion.  But  if  it  is  a  genuine  and  spontaneous  certainty  it 
is  as  permanent  throughout  life,  when  once  reached,  as  the 
similar  certainties  of  immortality  and  pre-existence. 

I  distinguish  the  genuine  experience  of  such  certainties 
from  the  ordinary  belief  in  the  testimony  of  others.  Such 
beliefs  are  opinions  which  may  be  imparted  to  suggestible 
people  but  also  lost  by  them.  The  genuine  intuition  is  a 
permanent  acquisition  reached  by  meditation  and  contempla- 
tion which  reveal  to  us  the  mystery  of  our  own  real  being. 
A  definite  knowledge  of  one's  self  is  the  metaphysical  explan- 
ation of  the  possibility  of  every  other  knowledge  of  anything 
else,  and  it  stands  as  open  as  the  evidence  of  the  senses  to 
all  those  who  seriously  endeavour  to  attain  it.  For  those 
who  have  no  such  experience  the  testimony  of  one  who  has 
it  is  simply  a  hypothesis  which  can  be  tested  by  the  wider 
objective  experience  of  sexual  life. 

Let  us,  therefore,  formulate  this  general  hypothesis  which 
will  help  us  to  account  for  the  facts  of  sexual  life.  Each  Self 
experiences  alternately,  in  phases  which  last  much  longer 
than  any  single  human  life,  two  opposite  spiritual  states 
which  within  our  earthly  existence  manifest  themselves  in 
bodies  of  opposite  sex.  These  alternate  phases  of  the  spirit 
follow  each  other  according  to  an  inward  determination,  as 
the  consequence  of  some  original  deviation  from  equilibrium, 
like  the  oscillations  of  a  pendulum.  This  original  deviation 
is  what  is  called  the  fall  of  man.  It  has  been  brought  about 
by  ourselves.  At  each  stage  we  may  be  more  or  less  distant 
from  equilibrium,  and  the  process  which  tends  towards  the 
opposite  state  goes  on  during  incarnation,  so  that  a  male 
spirit,  having  built  a  male  body,  may  in  its  inward  growth 
during  the  same  incarnation  reach  spiritual  femininity,  and 


62  WINCENTY   LUTOSLAWSKI: 

the  reverse.  This  explains  how  it  happens  that  we  know 
women  with  a  male  spirit  and  men  similar  to  women. 

The  difference  of  sex  is  known  to  us  by  intimate  experience 
and  cannot  be  stated  in  terms  of  any  other  order.  There  is 
no  virtue  or  vice  peculiar  to  one  sex  exclusively  of  the  other ; 
whatever  can  be  said  of  men  or  women  in  general  will  in 
particular  cases  apply  to  the  opposite  sex.  Even  the  defini- 
tion of  masculinity  as  predominance  of  activity  or  of  femi- 
ninity as  predominance  of  receptivity  will  not  exactly  fit  all 
the  individual  cases.  There  are  very  active  women  and  very 
passive  men.  Neither  is  courage  the  monopoly  of  man  nor 
purity  the  privilege  of  woman,  though  great  courage  is  more 
frequent  among  men  and  perfect  purity  among  women.  The 
tendency  to  define  sex  by  something  else  or  to  explain  the 
sexual  difference  by  a  combination  of  other  qualities  is  not 
compatible  with  a  full  and  clear  understanding  that  sex  is  a 
fundamental  mark  of  personality,  rooted  in  an  essential  state 
of  the  incarnating  spirit. 

The  sexes  are  really  different  and  opposite  classes  of  man- 
kind. There  is  an  agelong  opposition  between  them  and  a 
real  warfare,  the  most  genuine  class  warfare  in  human  life. 
The  predominance  of  muscular  strength  in  primitive  social 
conditions  has  kept  women  terrified  and  enslaved.  Every 
growth  of  civilisation  means  emancipation  of  women  from 
sheer  masculine  brutality  and  increases  their  influence  on 
social  and  political  life.  Women,  when  they  have  obtained 
in  every  respect  equality  of  opportunities  and  of  rights,  will 
still  remain  women  and  they  will  not  avail  themselves  of  all 
their  victories.  For  ages  they  have  freely  devoted  more  time 
and  industry  to  music  and  still  they  have  not  produced  a 
single  musical  composer  equal  to  the  greatest  male  musicians. 
Even  the  most  feminine  musical  genius  (Chopin)  has  taken 
a  male  body  for  his  incarnation.  If  our  parliaments  were 
filled  with  ladies,  it  is  not  likely  that  a  great  statesman 
would  arise  out  of  their  ranks.  Whenever  a  spirit  comes  to 
this  life  with  original  creative  faculties,  he  appears  as  a  male. 
Genius  is  essentially  masculine  and  even  great  talent  is  found 
oftener  in  men  than  in  women.  We  might  explain  this  by  the 
actual  social  condition  of  mankind,  in  which  men  still  prevail. 

If,  however,  there  is  somewhere  a  world  ruled  by  women, 
it  is  not  at  all  likely  to  follow  the  masculine  fancy  of  Aris- 
tophanes. On  the  contrary  such  a  world  would  be  probably 
a  better  world  than  ours.  *  Women  generally  are  better  than 
men.  They  are  less  selfish ;  but  they  have  also  less  in  them 
of  their  own  and  they  need  fecundation  in  body  and  mind  by 
men. 


A  THEOEY  OF  PEESONALITY.  G3 

Sexual  attraction  between  men  and  women,  from  the 
lowest  concupiscence  and  carnal  passion  to  the  highest  per- 
fection of  pure  love,  works  for  the  diminution  of  sexual  one- 
sidedness.  Carnality  exhausts  itself  in  man  by  loss  of  virility, 
in  women  by  maternity,  in  both  sexes  by  disease  resulting 
from  wrong  indulgence.  In  love  the  lovers  impregnate  each 
other  with  their  opposite  sexuality.  Men  acquire  the  feelings 
of  women  and  women  masculine  capacities.  Widows  have 
often  continued  the  work  of  their  deceased  husbands. 

In  the  long  struggle  between  the  sexes  there  is  one  great 
feminine  victory  due  to  Christianity  :  the  ideal  of  indissoluble 
marriage.  If  two  beings  of  opposite  sex,  with  the  full  under- 
standing of  what  it  means,  join  each  other  in  a  truly  indissol- 
uble union,  they  acquire  a  peculiar  sexual  experience,  not 
accessible  to  those  who  marry  on  the  understanding  that  they 
may  divorce.  Dissoluble  unions  are  inferior,  not  only  morally 
but  also  in  the  sense  of  mutual  absolute  possession  (and 
complete  satisfaction  of  all  the  senses),  to  true  indissoluble 
marriage. 

The  modern  agitation  in  favour  of  divorce  is  a  misguided 
aspiration  towards  the  same  ideal  of  indissoluble  marriage. 
People  want  to  dissolve  such  unions  as  are  not  true  marriages, 
in  order  to  enable  everybody  to  meet  the  true  partner  for  a 
really  indissoluble  marriage.  But  they  are  not  aware  that 
by  overthrowing  the  public  sanction  of  absolute  indissolu- 
bility  they  destroy  precisely  what  they  desire  to  obtain.  A 
divorced  woman  can  never  fully  believe  in  the  definitive 
character  of  a  new  union,  as  those  believe  who  take  the  risk 
of  a  solemn  affirmation  and  obligation  of  indissolubility, 
without  any  possible  recourse  to  law  in  order  to  justify  or 
mend  their  mistakes. 

The  indissolubility  of  marriage  was  unknown  in  pagan 
antiquity.  There  remains  even  now  a  higher  stage  of  in- 
dissolubility to  be  reached,- beyond  the  claims  of  the  Christian 
Church.  The  Church  sanctions  a  kind  of  polygamy  in  the 
successive  marriages  of  widows  and  widowers.  Strict  mono- 
gamy and  absolute  indissolubility  would  give  only  one  wife  to 
each  husband  in  each  life,  as  death  should  not  be  considered 
a  motive  for  divorce.  We  may  go  even  one  step  further  and 
imagine  the  same  feminine  Self  associated  as  wife  to  the  same 
masculine  Self  in  successive  lives.  Finally  such  a  close  and 
eternal  relation  of  two  spirits  might  exist  that  they  should 
have  been  to  each  other  alternately  husband  or  wife  in 
successive  incarnations. 

This  is  the  logical  development  of  the  ideal  of  strict  mono- 
gamy and  absolute  indissolubility  of  marriage.  Such  a  lasting 


64  WINCBNTY  LUTOSLAWSKI: 

link  explains  the  perfection  of  certain  marriages.  A  truly  in- 
dissoluble marriage  excludes  not  only  every  infidelity,  even 
previous  to  the  first  meeting  of  the  lovers,  or  posterior  to  the 
death  of  one  of  them,  but  also  every  quarrel  or  serious  dis- 
sension. If  such  a  perfectly  indissoluble  union  did  not  exist 
on  earth,  it  would  still  remain  the  dream  of  all  true  lovers. 
They  wish  to  share  mutually  all  their  thoughts  and  feelings, 
to  guess  rightly  each  other's  minds,  and  to  meet  naturally 
and  spontaneously  each  other's  wishes.  Such  perfect  love 
has  not  only  been  imagined  by  poets,  it  is  the  final  goal  of 
human  sexual  experience. 

But  the  more  we  progress  in  this  direction  of  absolute  per- 
fection of  love  and  indissolubility  of  marriage,  the  less  can  we 
expect  such  spiritual  realities  to  be  governed  by  external 
legislation  or  enforced  by  the  decrees  of  our  judges.  The  law 
cannot  ensure  love,  and  divorce  legislation  cannot  annul  truly 
indissoluble  marriage. 

With  the  increasing  perfection  of  social  life  public  opinion 
will  esteem  more  and  more  those  who  commit  no  mistakes  in 
their  sexual  choice.  But  those  unhappy  beings  who  have 
not  yet  reached  such  a  level  of  sexual  discrimination  will  in 
such  a  society  be  able  to  get  rid  of  insupportable  partners 
without  shocking  proceedings,  by  mutual  consent  and  the 
tacit  acquiescence  of  the  wise. 

We  cannot  expect  such  an  acquiescence  as  long  as  the 
mistakes  are  frequent  and  the  consequences  cruel  to  children 
and  other  innocent  victims  in  a  still  very  imperfect  society. 
We  are  responsible  for  all  the  consequences  of  our  mistakes. 
In  each  particular  case  many  things  should  be  carefully  con- 
sidered before  the  parents  of  a  child  dare  to  deprive  it  of  all 
that  the  common  life  of  a  family  implies. 

Endurance  of  an  imperfect  union  may  be  the  best  prepara- 
tion for  the  final  discovery  of  the  right  partner  in  a  future 
incarnation.  Those  who  have  once  made  a  mistake  are 
particularly  liable  to  commit  other  mistakes  and  therefore  no 
safer  advice  can  be  given  to  them  than  the  exhortation  to 
endure  what  they  have  brought  upon  themselves.  Those  few 
who  are  certain  of  having  discovered  their  true  and  definitive 
destiny  will  neither  ask  advice  nor  listen  to  it. 

The  doctrine  of  counterparts,  as  attributed  to  Aristophanes 
by  Plato  in  the  Symposium  and  later  popularised  by  Sweden- 
borg  and  Thomas  Lake  Harris,  is  not  a  passing  fancy.  It 
has  returned  again  and  again  with  obstinate  insistence  since 
the  tale  of  Tristan  and  Isolde  was  first  told.  Its  consequences 
are  very  serious ;  for,  if  each  of  us  has  only  one  true  counter- 
part, we  are  bound  to  give  up  every  other  union,  whatever 


A  THEORY   OF   PEESONALITY.  65 

the  consequences  may  be  to  us  or  to  others.  This  is  the 
romantic  conception  of  love,  justifying  every  breach  of  the 
law  and  every  infidelity  to  pledged  faith. 

On  the  other  hand,  if  love  is  not  such  a  transcendental  and 
absolute  reality,  if  true  marriage  depends  on  the  mutual  good- 
will of  any  two  persons  who  understand  the  rules  of  the  game, 
then  there  is  no  need  to  break  any  existing  bond  as  long  as 
we  can  improve  it,  and  it  would  be  silly  to  hope  that  a  future 
union  will  be  happier  at  the  cost  of  an  avowed  past  failure. 
This  is  the  classical  doctrine  which  condemns  the  romantic 
view  as  a  perverse  invention  of  the  evil  spirit.  Social  peace 
and  moral  order  seem  to  be  safer  in  an  un romantic  world, 
where  the  stability  of  sexual  unions  does  not  run  the  risk  of 
sudden  revelations  which  overthrow  every  existing  link  and 
obligation . 

According  to  the  current  view  the  classical  doctrine  is 
Christian  and  romantic  madness  is  pagan.  But  the  original 
classical  marriage  of  Greek  or  Hebrew  antiquity  has  been 
always  essentially  dissoluble,  while  indissolubility  has  been 
introduced  into  the  marriage  laws  by  Christianity ;  and  it  is 
nothing  else  than  the  legal  expression  of  the  romantic  craving 
for  absolute  union.  Romantic  love  is  the  spiritual  justification 
of  Christian  marriage.  Christianity  has  established  as  uni- 
versal law  what  had  been  the  highest  voluntary  experience 
of  exceptional  lovers.  The  fulfilment  of  the  Christian  law  is 
humanly  possible  only  under  the  condition  of  romantic  love. 
The  miracle  of  such  a  love  has  been  discovered  by  mediaeval 
poets  and  confirmed  by  such  enthusiasts  as  Swedenborg  or 
Thomas  Lake  Harris.  A  single  example  of  positive  ex- 
perience is  more  decisive  than  thousands  of  failures  which 
appear  to  contradict  such  experience.  Two  lovers  who  are 
certain  that  they  were  made  by  God  for  each  other  and  for 
nobody  else,  are  more  reliable  witnesses  than  any  number  of 
Don  Juans  who  have  sought  their  counterpart  in  vain  and 
have  still  gone  on  believing  in  final  success  against  their 
own  experience. 

But  even  if  we  grant  that  such  reliable  witnesses  exist, 
their  testimony  does  not  justify  a  sweeping  generalisation. 
They  may  be  very  rare  exceptions  and  are  likely  to  be  such 
exceptions,  for  perfect  love  can  exist  only  between  perfect 
beings  at  a  very  high  stage  of  personal  development.  Such 
perfect  beings  will  not  easily  break  existing  obligations  even 
if  they  have  made  a  mistake  in  marrying  the  wrong  person. 

For  the  generality  of  mankind  there  is  nothing  lost  if  every- 
body endures  what  he  has  brought  upon  himself  by  his  own  free 
decision.  Those  exceptional  beings  who  are  fit  to  have  a  true 

5 


66  WINCENTY  LUTOSLAWSKI: 

counterpart  are  not  likely  to  be  deceived  by  rash  decisions 
into  unholy  unions  or  they  will  find  a  way  out  of  such  a  wrong 
union  without  doing  harm  to  anybody. 

Thus  we  can  conciliate  the  classical  and  the  romantic  view 
of  love  and  marriage.  Classical  marriage,  if  faithfully  kept, 
prepares  romantic  love  in  a  future  incarnation,  or  is  the  out- 
ward form  of  an  existing  romantic  love. 

The  difference  of  sex  influences  also  other  human  relations 
besides  love  and  marriage,  namely  friendship,  fatherhood, 
motherhood,  and  brotherhood.  There  is  the  possibility  of 
pure  friendship  between  persons  of  different  sex,  which  will 
not  lead  to  exclusive  love  and  will  still  be  a  feeling  different 
from  friendship  between  persons  of  the  same  sex.  The  full 
growth  of  such  friendships  free  from  temptations  appears  to 
be  conditioned  by  the  experience  of  true  exclusive  love  which 
feels  no  jealousy.  Only  those  who  have  found  their  love  can 
peacefully  enjoy  innocent  friendships  with  the  other  sex. 
Otherwise  every  such  friendship  is  threatened  by  the  sudden 
revelation  of  love  which  spoils  its  purity. 

The  real  differentiation  of  sexual  love  and  sexual  friendship 
presupposes  the  emancipation  from  superficial  sensual  attach- 
ments which  are  not  exclusive.  There  is  a  succession  of 
degrees  in  sexual  experience  which  starts  by  animal  carnality 
and  ends  in  true  love  distinguished  from  pure  sexual  friend- 
ship. That  so  many  men  still  disbelieve  in  such  friendship 
proves  only  that  they  are  equally  ignorant  of  true  exclusive 
love  and  see  in  every  woman  a  possible  mistress. 

The  relation  between  father  and  daughter  or  mother  and 
son  implies  true  friendship  and  something  besides  which  is 
sexual  fatherhood  and  sexual  motherhood.  A  father  loves 
his  daughter  otherwise  than  his  son,  but  such  a  differentiation 
of  sexual  feelings  is  the  ripe  fruit  of  a  long  growth  of  the 
.soul. 

Also  the  relation  between  brother  and  sister  differs  from 
ihe  brotherhood  prevailing  between  persons  of  the  same  sex. 
No  definition  of  these  feelings  is  possible  and  very  few  in- 
dividuals experience  them  fully.  They  are  not  a  necessary 
consequence  of  the  common  origin  of  two  persons  from  the 
same  parents,  as  physiological  brotherhood  does  not  necessar- 
ily imply  spiritual  brotherhood,  and  this  last  is  possible  also 
without  consanguinity. 

The  influence  of  sex  permeates  not  only  all  personal 
relations  between  persons  of  different  sex,  but  also  every 
manifestation  of  human  activity.  Men  and  women  are  able 
to  do  the  same  things  in  a  different  way  and  we  require  a 
wide  experience  of  life  with  a  deep  consciousness  of  sex  to 


A   THEORY  OF   PEESONALITY.  67 

appreciate  this  diversity,  which  confirms  the  hypothesis  that 
sexual  difference  has  its  root  in  a  pre-existent  state  of  the 
Self  and  not  in  the  structure  of  our  bodies. 

The  form  of  the  body  is  a  symbolic  expression  of  those 
spiritual  realities  which  appear  as  masculine  expansion  and 
feminine  receptivity,  or  virile  strength  and  virginal  beauty. 
There  are  degrees  of  sexuality  in  body  and  mind  and  a  person 
may  be  more  or  less  manly  or  womanly,  in  spirit  as  well  as 
in  the  body.  The  body  does  not  always  correspond  exactly 
to  the  spirit,  because  we  have  such  bodies  as  are  the  expression 
of  our  spirit  at  the  time  of  conception,  with  the  limitations 
imposed  by  the  chosen  ancestry.  The  spirit  builds  the  body 
out  of  the  blood  furnished  by  the  parents  and  every  builder 
is  hampered  by  the  imperfection  of  the  materials  used. 

Conception  depends  on  a  peculiar  relation  of  three  spirits, 
those  of  the  parents  and  the  incarnating  Self.  Only  when 
true  love  unites  the  parents  can  a  Self  of  the  highest  kind 
accept  their  body.  Imperfect  unions  of  selfish  and  carnal 
people  furnish  the  opportunity  for  the  incarnation  of  lower 
spirits.  The  emotional  and  spiritual  attitude  of  the  parents 
towards  each  other  and  towards  God  in  their  union  has  a 
greater  influence  on  the  character  of  their  children  than 
physical  heredity.  Parents  who  are  aware  of  this  may 
attract  towards  their  bodies  by  humble  prayer  and  faith,  in 
unselfish  devotion,  the  highest  kind  of  incarnating  spirits, 
who  come  down  on  earth  not  because  they  crave  for  sensual 
life,  but  because  they  wish  and  intend  to  serve  and  to  help 
others  by  improving  the  conditions  of  human  life  on  earth. 

This  incarnation  of  the  highest  spirits,  of  men  of  genius 
and  of  Saints,  has  been  usually  worked  unconsciously  by 
pious  parents  united  in  true  love  and  guided  by  higher 
inspiration.  Conscious  striving  for  such  a  fecundation  trans- 
forms deeply  the  marriage  relation  and  may  be  considered  as 
the  highest  human  Art,  as  it  calls  into  being  not  images  or 
symbols  like  the  other  arts,  but  living  persons,  incarnated 
spirits.  They  receive  a  strong  and  beautiful  body  from  their 
loving  parents  and  they  give  them  heavenly  bliss ;  for  there 
is  no  joy  greater  than  the  rejoicing  of  a  father  or  a  mother  at 
their  children's  attainments,  if  their  whole  life  was  directed 
towards  this  goal. 

How  such  a  result  can  be  obtained  those  who  are  united  in 
a  consciously  indissoluble  union  for  mutual  help  towards 
ideal  perfection  learn  easily  by  claiming  boldly  from  above 
the  necessary  inspiration  and  acting  up  to  the  light  which  is 
never  denied  to  them.  They  will  be  guided  from  step  to  step 
in  their  endeavours ;  and  every  pair  of  lovers  entering  this 


68      WINCENTY  LTJTOSLAWSKI :   A  THEORY  OF   PEESONALITY. 

noble  competition  will  be  amply  rewarded  for  their  unselfish 
devotion  and  their  repudiation  of  vulgar  gratifications. 

If  our  human  sexual  life  is  thus  explained  by  the  con- 
ception of  a  spiritual  sexuality  pre-existing  to  its  bodily 
expression,  there  arises  the  difficulty  of  explaining  how 
it  is  possible  that  sexual  life  extends  beyond  and  below 
humanity,  while  we  cannot  credit  animals  with  the  spiritu- 
ality of  human  loves.  Sexual  life  in  beings  lower  than  man- 
kind seems  to  throw  a  singular  light  on  human  sexual  life 
which  in  external  appearances  sometimes  resembles  closely 
that  of  lower  animals. 

The  only  way  out  of  this  difficulty  is  the  supposition  that 
what  we  know  as  the  evolution  from  the  lower  to  the  higher 
forms  of  the  body  is  not  a  primitive  process,  but  a  con- 
sequence of  a  previous  fall  of  the  spirit.  Thus  though,  in  the 
history  of  our  earth,  life  seems  to  have  risen  from  animality 
to  humanity,  humanity  is  older  in  the  universe  than  animality 
and  there  is  truth  in  the  tradition  that  the  creation  of  angels 
has  preceded  the  creation  of  man. 

Therefore  we  are  right  in  interpreting  the  sexuality  of 
animals  by  human  sexual  experience,  not  the  reverse.  In 
every  fecundation  a  spirit  precedes  the  body  and  is  builder 
of  the  body.  The  sexual  difference  in  the  animal  world  has 
the  same  fundamental  meaning  as  in  the  human  world,  only 
heredity  dominates  much  more  the  generation  of  animals, 
without  excluding  the  possibility  of  feelings  and  strivings  in 
animal  consciousness  which  are  akin  to  human  experience 
and  imply  an  obscure  tendency  towards  the  recovery  of  the 
lost  equilibrium,  a  tendency  which  is  at  the  bottom  of  the 
mystery  of  sexual  differentiation. 

The  future  equilibrium,  as  the  last  goal,  need  not  be  the 
same  as  the  lost  equilibrium  or  the  starting  point  of  sexual 
life.  In  this  future  equilibrium  sexual  difference  may  still 
persist ;  and  the  Catholic  cult  of  the  Virgin,  which  is  also  a 
manifestation  of  sexual  consciousness  in  the  believers,  would 
thus  find  its  justification. 

Sex  would  be  then  the  result  of  a  felix  culpa,  which,  how- 
ever, for  its  atonement  does  not  require  the  annulment  of 
this  duality  of  being,  which  is  known  to  us  as  sexual  life. 
The  mere  onesidedness  of  sex  may  be  overcome  otherwise 
than  by  the  monotony  of  asexuality  and  the  whole  of  human 
sexual  experience  would  then  appear  as  a  device  of  God  for 
the  gradual  extinction  of  our  selfishness  by  showing  us  in  the 
opposite  sex  an  object  of  our  most  immediate  and  spon- 
taneous love. 


V.— DISCUSSION. 
THE  MEANING  OF  'MEANING'. 

DB.  SCHILLEB'S  reply  in  the  October  MIND  to  my  discussion  in  the 
July  issue  contains  a  number  of  misunderstandings  and  misstate- 
ments  of  my  views  which  I  feel  it  my  duty  to  correct. 

(1)  I  did  not  say  that,  in  looking  for  the  *  I,'  what  my  "  attention 
really  fastens  on  is  some   obscure  bodily   sensation — if   not  the 
tension  in  his  head  muscles,  then  the  rush  of  blood  in  his  arteries  "  : 
I  said  this  is  what  Dr.  Schiller's  attention  really  fastens  on  when 
he   thinks   he   has   immediate   experience   of   *  activity ' — in   this 
following  James.     For  me,  the  '  I '  is  not  one  datum  or  feature  of 
experience   among  others;  it  is  all  experience   de-objectified.      In 
perceiving,  that  is,  a  sensuous  state  (of  sound,  taste,  smell,  vision) 
is  used  as  the  sign  of  an  object ;  it  conveys  the  object  only  in  the 
form  of  a  '  meaning ' ;  and  it  does  so  because  we  adopt  the  motor 
attitude  appropriate  to  the  object.     Now  at  the  moment  of  per- 
ception, being  intent  on  this  meaning,  we  cannot  be  aware  of  the 
sensuous  state.      That   it   existed  at  that  moment,  however,  we 
learn  in  retrospection,  when  we  consider  that  the  meaning  was 
brought  before  us  only  by  the  sensuous  state  used  as  a  sign — in 
other  words,  that  the  apparent  existence  of  the  object  was  really 
the  existence  of  the  sensuous  state  or  '  I '. 

(2)  Nothing  could  be   more   untrue,  then,  than  to  say  that  I 
make  the  ego  an  "  illusion  "  ;  it  is  rather  those  who  look  for  it  in 
some  single  feature  of  consciousness,  such  as  '  activity,'  who  are 
in  danger  of  making  it  an  illusion.    Dr.  Schiller  says  that  '  activity ' 
is  not  an  observable  object :  but  then  what  is  his  empirical  evidence 
for  it?     Does  he  distinguish  between  things  that  are  observable 
objects  and  things  that  are  merely  experienced  ?     An  ego  that  is  a 
sensuous  state  can  be  found — in  retrospection  as  the  ego,  and  even 
in  perception  as  the  apparent  existence  of  the  object.     Or  is  the 
fact  to  which  he  refers  our  general  grasp  of  the  situation,    our 
sense  of  our  total  meaning,  conceived  as  one  and  directive?     I 
would  point  out  that  this  is  a  sense — i.e.  it  has  a  sensuous  state, 
however  vague  and  difficult   to  classify,  as   its  vehicle,    and   so 
conforms  to  my  theory  of  the  ego.     I  wish  I  could  feel  sure  that 
Dr.  Schiller  is  not  trying  to  re-establish  that  conception  of  con- 
sciousness as  a  *  pigment '  or  '  menstruum '  which  James   con- 
demned in  his  article  'Does  "Consciousness"  Exist?'     He  seems 
to  me  to  be  drifting  back  from  the  strictly  empirical  psychology  of 
James  to  something  like  a  spiritualistic  psychology. 


70  C.   A.    STKONG  : 

(3)  Nor  can  I  admit  that  my  sensationalist  '  I '  is  less  truly 
active    than   his   quasi-spiritualist  '  I '.      Sensuous  states,  on  my 
theory,  are  efficacious  (it  is  only  given-essences  or  '  meanings '  that 
are  not  so) ;  a  motor  attitude  is  necessary  to  constitute  cognition,  and 
to  make  the  sensuous  state  convey  a  meaning ;  the  '  I,'  considered 
with  reference  to  its  consequences,  is  will :  what  excuse  there  is 
for  labelling  me  an  '  intellectualist '  and  a  contemner  of  activity,. 
I   am  unable   to  see.     Unless  it  be  that  I  do  not  let  the  will 
co-operate   in   determining  the  content  of  knowledge,  but  wish 
cognition  to  show  me  the  universe  as  it  is. 

(4)  Dr.  Schiller  says   I   consider   only   one   case   of   meaning, 
"  that  in  which  an  '  object '  is  said  to  '  mean  so-and-so,'  "  and  that 
I  do  not  derive  '  personal '  meaning.     The  case  I  consider  is  not 
that  in  which  an  object  means  something  else,  but  that  in  which  I 
mean  an  object — as  I  have  to  do  in  order  to  think  of  it.     How 
meaning  can  be  more  personal  than  this,  I  should  like  him  to 
explain. 

It  may  not  be  amiss  to  recall  here  that  James  discussed  this 
question  of  the  nature  of  meaning,  in  an  article  called  '  A  World  of 
Pure  Experience '  (reprinted'  in  Essays  in  Radical  Empiricism), 
and  developed  a  theory  very  similar  to  that  which  I  defend.  A 
couple  of  quotations  will  show  this.  "Suppose  me  to  be  sitting 
here  in  my  library  at  Cambridge,  at  ten  minutes'  walk  from 
1  Memorial  Hall,'  and  to  be  thinking  truly  of  the  latter  object.  My 
mind  may  have  before  it  only  the  name,  or  it  may  have  a  clear 
image,  or  it  may  have  a  very  dim  image  of  the  hall.  ...  If  you 
ask  me  what  I  MEAN  [small  caps  mine]  by  my  image,  and  I  can 
tell  you  nothing;  or  if  I  fail  to  point  or  lead  you  towards  the 
Harvard  Delta ;  or  if,  being  led  by  you,  I  am  uncertain  whether 
the  Hall  I  see  be  what  I  had  in  mind  or  not ;  you  would  rightly 
deny  that  I  had  '  meant '  that  particular  hall  at  all.  .  .  .  On  the 
other  hand,  if  I  can  lead  you  to  the  hall  ...  if  in  its  presence  I 
feel  my  idea,  however  imperfect  it  may  have  been,  to  have  led 
hither  and  to  be  now  terminated  .  .  .  why  then  my  soul  was. 
prophetic,  and  my  idea  must  be,  and  by  common  consent  would 
be,  called  cognisant  of  reality.  That  percept  was  what  I  meant  " 
(55-56).  What  is  important  in  this  passage  is  the  non-existence  of 
any  special  function  of  meaning — its  non-existence  psychologically, 
or  as  a  datum  of  introspection,  that  is,  for  epistemologically  I 
certainly  do  mean  the  object.  When  such  a  process  of  experiential 
conduction  through  intermediaries  unrolls  itself,  says  James,  "  their 
starting-point  thereby  becomes  a  knoiver  and  their  terminus  an  object 
meant  or  knoivn"  (57). 

I  do  not  mean  to  assent  unreservedly  to  this  account  of  know- 
ing or  meaning,  for  (a)  the  intermediaries  do  not,  as  James  him- 
self observes,  need  to  be  actually  passed  through  in  order  that  the 
knowing  relation  may  exist;  (b)  they  do  not  even  need  to  be 
capable  of  being  passed  through,  in  the  form  of  experiences :  as 
is  shown  by  the  fact  that  we  can  know  or  mean  the  past,  or  a 


THE    MEANING   OF    '   MEANING'.  71 

distant  object  as  it  is  at  this  moment,  or  another  mind.  It  is  the 
actually  existing  physical  relations  between  the  object  and  our 
mind  that  enable  us  to  mean  it.  Hence  a  visual  sensation,  whose 
sufficient  resemblance  to  the  object  is  guaranteed  by  the  fact  that 
it  was  called  forth  by  stimuli  from  it,  may  mean  or  know  that 
object  provided  it  leads  us  to  point  toward  it  or  to  perform  actions 
addressed  to  it ;  and  perception  requires  to  have  no  greater  clair- 
voyancy  or  intuitive  power  than  this.  Meaning  is  not  primarily 
and  originally  a  relation  of  a  mental  image  to  a  sensation ;  it  is, 
in  its  earliest  form,  a  relation  of  a  sensation  to  the  external  object 
which  it  enables  us  to  cognise. 

(5)  Dr.  Schiller  is  impatient  with  me  because  I  attempt,  realis- 
tically, to  account  for  meaning  by  means  of  relations  to  things 
outside  the  mind,  and  will  not  content  myself^  as  he  does,  with 
merely  describing  the  experience  of  meaning.  If  I  understand 
him  rightly,  when  he  goes  to  Switzerland  to  climb,  the  mountains 
are  a  temporary  hypothesis  which  is  true  because  it  works,  bufe 
which  ceases  to  be  true  when  he  returns  to  Oxford.  Or,  if  he 
attributes  to  them  a  greater  degree  of  reality  than  this  (as  I  hope), 
then  I  have  a  right  to  consider  his  body  and  the  relations  between 
it  and  them  in  explaining  how  he  can  think  of  or  '  mean'  them. 

Finally,  may  I  say  that  it  was  not  from  any  impulse  of  chivalry, 
as  he  suggests,  that  I  rushed  to  the  aid  of  beauty  in  distress  in  the 
person  of  Mr.  Kussell,  but  because  all  three  of  the  learned  dis- 
putants appeared  to  me  to  be,  in  one  form  or  another,  phenom- 
enalists,  and  because,  even  after  Dr.  Schiller's  two  valuable 
papers,  no  reference  (so  far  as  I  remember)  to  a  possible  bearing 
of  my  form  of  realism  on  the  question  had  yet  been  made.  I 
wished  to  maintain,  against  Mr.  Eussell,  that  there  is  no  good 
ground  for  holding  that  mental  images  can  signify  to  the  mind 
things  beyond  themselves,  but  that  sensations  cannot  do  so ;  that, 
consequently,  the  distinction  between  sense-datum  and  sensation 
is  a  valid  distinction.  Dr.  Schiller  was  well  advised  in  raising 
the  problem  of  the  nature  of  meaning;  it  is  admirably  adapted 
to  take  us  to  the  roots  of  things ;  but  he  must  not  be  surprised 
if  it  turns  out  that  physical  objects  are  known  by  our  '  meaning  ' 
them,  and  that  how  we  can  mean  them  is  explained  by  certain 
relations  between  physical  objects. 

C.  A.  STKONG. 


VI.— CEITICAL  NOTICES. 

A  Treatise  on  Probability.  BY  J.  M.  KEYNES,  Fellow  of  King's 
College,  Cambridge.  London  :  Macmillan  &  Co.  Ltd.,  1921. 
Pp.  xi,  466. 

Mr.  KEYNES'S  long  awaited  work  on  Probability  is  now  published, 
and  will  at  once  take  its  place  as  the  best  treatise  on  the  logical 
foundations  of  the  subject.  The  present  reviewer  well  remembers 
going  over  the  proofs  of  the  earlier  parts  of  it  in  the  long  vacation 
of  1914  with  Mr.  Keynes  and  Mr.  Russell.  From  these  innocent 
pleasures  Mr.  Keynes  was  suddenly  hauled  away  on  a  friendly 
sidecar  to  advise  the  authorities  in  London  on  the  moratorium  and 
the  foreign  exchanges.  Mr.  Eussell  (like  the  foreign  exchanges) 
received  a  shock,  from  which  he  has  never  wholly  recovered,  in 
learning  that  the  logic  books  had  been  deceiving  him  by  their  re- 
iterated assertions  that  "man  is  a  rational  animal  ";  and  the 
Treatise  on  Probability  was  held  up  till  this  year. 

The  present  treatise  is  essentially  philosophical  rather  than 
mathematical,  although  it  contains  a  fair  amount  of  mathematics. 
It  is  divided  into  five  parts.  The  first  defines  probability  and  dis- 
cusses how  far  it  can  be  measured.  The  second  gives  the  funda- 
mental theorems  of  probability  in  strict  logical  form.  This  part 
owes  a  great  deal  to  Mr.  W.  E.  Johnson,  to  whose  magnificent 
work  on  this  subject  Mr.  Keynes  acknowledges  his  great  obligations. 
Indeed  the  Muse  of  Probability  seems  to  have  fixed  her  seat  at 
King's  College,  Cambridge,  of  which  both  Mr.  Keynes  and  Mr. 
Johnson  are  fellows.  The  third  part  deals  with  the  logical  prin- 
ciples of  inductive  and  analogical  generalisation ;  and  the  fifth 
with  the  connected,  but  more  complex,  problem  of  inductive 
correlation  or  statistical  inference.  In  between  these  two  is 
sandwiched  Part  IV.,  which  is  entitled  "  Some  Philosophical  Appli- 
cations of  Probability ".  This  is  concerned  with  a  number  of 
historically  interesting  problems,  and  in  particular  with  the  appli- 
cation of  probability  to  ethics.  At  the  end  of  the  work  Mr.  Keynes 
provides  an  admirable  bibliography  of  books  and  articles  on 
probability  and  kindred  subjects. 

In  this  review  I  shall  try  to  give  an  outline  of  Mr.  Keynes's 
theory.  I  shall  not  have  many  serious  criticisms  to  make,  because 
I  am  substantially  in  agreement  with  him,  and  where  I  am  not 
persuaded  by  his  arguments  the  subject  is  so  difficult  that  I  have 
little  of  value  to  suggest  as  an  alternative  to  his  views. 

The  fundamental  thesis  of  the  book  is  that  probability  is  a  rela- 


J.  M.  KETNES,  A  Treatise  on  Probability.  73 

tion  between  propositions,  which  may  be  compared  with  implication. 
When  p  implies  q  the  belief  that  p  is  true  justifies  an  equally  strong 
belief  in  q.  But  there  are  numberless  cases  where  a  belief  in  p 
justifies  a  certain  degree  of  belief  in  q,  but  does  not  justify  so 
strong  a  belief  in  q  as  we  have  in  p.  In  such  cases  there  is  a 
•certain  logical  relation  between  p  and  q,  and  this  relation  is  of  the 
utmost  importance  for  logic.  But  it  is  not  the  relation  of  impli- 
cation. It  is  this  other  relation  with  which  probability  is  con- 
cerned. This  probability  relation  is  capable  of  degree,  since  it  may 
justify  a  more  or  a  less  confident  belief  in  q.  The  typical  probability 
statement  is  of  the  form  "p  has  to  q  a  probability  relation  of 
degree  x".  Implication  may  perhaps  be  regarded  as  the  strongest 
probability  relation,  or  better  as  a  limit  of  all  possible  probability 
relations. 

There  is  however  a  very  important  difference,  which  is  not 
merely  one  of  degree,  between  the  implicative  and  the  probability 
relations.  There  is  nothing  corresponding  to  the  Principle  of 
Assertion  in  probability.  If  one  proposition  implies  another  and 
we  know  that  the  first  is  true  we  are  justified  by  the  Principle  of 
Assertion  in  going  on  to  believe  the  second  by  itself,  and  in  drop- 
ping all  reference  to  the  first.  We  can  never  do  this  in  probabil- 
ity. We  can  never  get  beyond  statements  of  the  form  "p  has 
such  and  such  a  probability  with  respect  to  the  datum  q  ".  Pro- 
positions are  true  or  false  in  themselves,  though  we  may  need  to 
know  their  relations  to  other  propositions  in  order  to  know  whether 
they  are  true  or  false.  But  probability  is  of  its  very  nature 
relative.  When  we  talk  of  the  probability  of  a  proposition  this 
phrase  is  always  elliptical,  as  when  we  say  that  the  distance  of 
London  is  120  miles.  We  simply  assume  that  the  person  to 
whom  we  are  speaking  will  supply  from  his  own  mind  the  same 
data  as  we  are  taking.  Two  important  consequences  flow  from 
this.  In  the  first  place,  a  proposition  may  be  highly  probable  with 
respect  to  certain  data  and  yet  be  false.  Its  turning  out  to  be  false 
makes  no  difference  whatever  to  the  fact  that  it  is  highly  probable 
with  respect  to  these  data.  Secondly,  one  and  the  same  proposi- 
tion may  have  many  different  probabilities  at  the  same  time,  so 
long  as  the  data  are  different  in  each  case.  In  particular  a  pro- 
position may  be  highly  probable  with  respect  to  a  certain  set  of 
data  and  highly  improbable  with  respect  to  another  set  of 
data  which  includes  the  first  set  as  a  part.  Thus,  if  the  only  fact 
that  you  know  about  a  man  is  that  he  has  recently  swallowed 
arsenic,  it  is  highly  probable  with  respect  to  these  data  that  he  will 
be  dead  in  the  next  half  hour.  If  you  afterwards  get  the  additional 
piece  of  information  that  he  has  taken  an  emetic,  the  probability 
that  he  will  die  in  the  next  half  hour,  on  the  combined  data,  is 
much  smaller.  Neither  probability  is  in  any  way  more  "  correct  " 
than  the  other.  This  essential  relativity  of  probability  is  abso- 
lutely fundamental,  and  most  previous  expositions  have  suffered 
by  failing  to  grasp  it. 


74  CEITICAL   NOTICES  : 

To  express  these  facts  Mr.  Keynes  takes  over  a  useful  symbol 
from  Mr.  Johnson.  He  writes  q/p  =  x  for  "  the  probability  of  q 
with  respect  to  the  datum p  is  of  magnitude  x'1.  Two  questions- 
at  once  arise :  (1)  Can  probability  always  be  measured  ?  and  (2) 
Why  do  we  commonly  prefer  a  probability  with  respect  to  wider 
data  to  a  probability  with  respect  to  narrower  data?  These 
questions  are  dealt  with  by  Mr.  Keynes  in  two  chapters  in  the 
first  part. 

(1)  Mr.  Keynes  argues  that  there  is  no  reason  to  suppose  that 
all  probabilities  fall  into  a  single  scale.  All  indeed  lie  between 
certain  truth  and  certain  falsehood,  but  there  may  be  innumerable 
series  leading  from  the  one  to  the  other.  It  is  only  probabilities 
that  lie  in  the  same  course  that  can  be  directly  compared.  Two 
different  courses  may  cut  each  other  at  one  or  more  points,  i.e.r 
there  may  be  certain  probabilities  which  are  common  to  several 
different  series.  When  this  happens  there  is  a  possibility  of  in- 
directly comparing  two  probabilities  in  different  series  by  compar- 
ing both  with  one  that  is  common  to  the  two  series.  But,  even 
when  we  confine  ourselves  to  the  probabilities  of  a  single  series, 
there  is  no  guarantee  that  we  shall  be  able  to  set  up  a  consistent 
system  of  numerical  measures  for  them.  Not  every  series  of 
comparable  magnitudes  is  measurable.  The  mathematicians  have 
naturally  exaggerated  the  amount  of  numerically  measurable  pro- 
bability in  the  wprld ;  and,  when  they  came  across  probabilities 
that  were  not  comparable,  or,  if  comparable,  not  numerically 
measurable,  they  passed  by  and  "  thanked  God  that  they  were 
rid  of  a  rogue  ".  Probabilities  are  only  measurable  in  the  com- 
paratively rare  cases  where  we  have  a  field  of  possibilities  which 
can  be  split  up  disjunctively  into  exhaustive,  exclusive,  and 
equiprobable  alternatives.  This  does  happen  in  games  of  chance 
and  in  the  "bag"  problems  in  which  mathematicians  exercise 
themselves,  but  not  in  many  other  cases. 

It  must  be  noticed  that  this  view  of  Mr.  Keynes's  is  much  more 
radical  than  the  view  that  all  probabilities  are  theoretically 
measurable,  but  that  in  most  cases  the  practical  difficulties  are 
insuperable.  Mr.  Keynes  points  out  that  there  is  one  and  only 
one  theory  of  probability  on  which  the  latter  view  is  plausible.. 
{This  is  the  Frequency  Theory,  which  he  proceeds  to  discuss. 

There  is  something  bluff  and  Anglo-Saxon  about  the  Frequency 
Theory,  which  no  doubt  accounts  for  its  extreme  popularity  with 
the  Island  Eace  in  general  and  with  Prof.  Whitehead  in  particular. 
Moreover  there  is  a  real  but  rather  complex  connexion  between 
probability  and  frequency  by  way  of  Bernoulli's  Theorem ;  and 
the  very  narrow  limits  within  which  that  theorem  and  its  converse 
can  be  applied  have  been  overlooked  by  most  people,  as  Mr. 
Keynes  points  out  in  the  later  parts  of  the  present  work.  Thus 
there  are  many  excuses  for  accepting  the  Frequency  Theory. 
Mr.  Keynes  has  little  difficulty  in  showing  that,  in  the  simple- 
minded  form  in  which  it  appears  in  Venn's  Logic  of  Chance,  it  i& 


j.  M.  KEYNES,  A   Treatise  on  Probability.  75 

unsatisfactory,  and  that  Venn  tacitly  assumes  in  many  places  a  sense 
of  probability  other  than  that  which  is  laid  down  in  his  definitions. 
Prof.  Whitehead's  form  of  the  theory,  as  might  be  expected,  is  a 
good  deal  more  subtle.  Unfortunately  it  is  not  easy  to  make  out 
exactly  what  it  is.  Mr.  Keynes  states  it  in  the  way  in  which  he 
has  understood  it  from  private  correspondence,  but  admits  that  he 
may  be  mistaken  about  Whitehead's  meaning.  It  is  therefore 
hardly  profitable  for  a  third  person  to  discuss  this  form  of  the 
theory.  But  it  is  open  to  a  reviewer  to  point  out  what  seems  to 
him  to  be  a  fallacy  in  Mr.  Keynes's  arguments  against  the  theory. 
Keynes  argues  that  Whitehead's  form  of  the  theory  shares  with 
Venn's  the  defect  that  it  cannot  satisfactorily  explain  the  funda- 
mental axiom  connecting  the  probability  of  a  disjunctive  proposi- 
tion with  the  probabilities  of  its  separate  parts,  i.e.,  the  proposition 

(pvq)/h  =  p/h  +  q/h  -  pq/li. 

On  the  Frequency  Theory,  as  interpreted  by  Mr.  Keynes,  the 
datum  h  determines  a  certain  class  a  of  propositions  of  which 
p  is  a  member,  a  certain  class  /?  of  which  q  is  a  member,  and 
certain  classes  y  and  8  of  which  the  propositions  pq  and  pvq  are 
respectively  members.  The  probability  of  p  with  respect  to  h 
is  then  defined  as  the  ratio  of  the  number  of  true  propositions 
in  the  class  a  to  the  total  number  of  propositions  in  this  class. 
Similar  definitions  apply,  mutatis  mutandis,  to  the  probabilities 
of  q,  pq,  and  pvq,  respectively.  He  then  points  out,  quite  truly, 
that  the  question  whether  the  fundamental  addition-theorem  men- 
tioned above  will  hold  at  all  depends  entirely  on  what  particular 
classes,  a,  /?,  y  and  8,  the  datum  h  does  determine  for  the  four 
propositions  in  question.  So  far  I  quite  agree,  and  think  that 
this  is  a  very  serious  difficulty  in  the  way  of  the  theory  in  question. 
But  Mr.  Keynes  then  proceeds  to  tell  us  what  must  be  the  values 
of  the  classes,  a,  ft,  y,  and  8,  if  the  equation  is  to  hold.  He  says 
that  8  must  be  the  class  of  propositions  of  the  form  p\q,  where 
p  is  a  member  of  a  and  q  of  ft ;  and  that  y  must  be  the  class  a/3 
of  propositions.  It  is  very  easy  to  make  up  simple  concrete  ex- 
amples to  disprove  this ;  i.e.,  to  make  up  examples  in  which  the 
fundamental  theorem  does  not  hold  even  when  the  classes  of 
reference  are  determined  in  this  particular  way.  But  it  is  better 
to  disprove  it  quite  generally.  It  can  be  shown  that  the  number 
of  propositions  in  Mr.  Keynes's  class  8  is  (a)  (/3)  -  (a/?)/2  -  (aft)*/'*. 
It  can  also  be  shown  that  the  number  of  true  propositions  in 
this  class  is  : — 

(«,)(/?)  +  G8,)(«)  -  KX/»r)  -  (a/3),  (aft)  +  («0:/a  -  («0T/2 

where  (a)  =  the  number  of  propositions  in  the  class  a ;  (aT)  means 
the  number  of  true  propositions  in  the  class  a ;  and  similar  mean- 
ings attach  to  the  other  symbols.  If  the  fundamental  equation 


76  CEITICAL  NOTICES: 

is  to  hold,  the  ratio  of  the  second  expression  to  the  first  must 
be  equal  to — 

W  ,  («  _  (°&i 

(a)    +    (ft)          (aft)' 

It  is  quite  obvious  that  this  will  not  in  general  be  true;  and 
therefore  that  either  Mr.  Keynes  or  I  have  made  some  blunder 
in  the  algebra  of  classes.  I  am  pretty  certain  that  Mr.  Keynes 
is  wrong,  but  of  course  I  may  be  wrong  too.  However  this  may 
be,  the  real  force  of  Mr.  Keynes's  general  criticism  is  not  diminished, 
even  if  he  has  made  an  algebraical  slip  here. 

If  the  measurement  and  comparison  of  probabilities  be  pos- 
sible only  in  a  few  specially  favourable  cases  it  is  peculiarly  im- 
portant to  be  sure  what  those  cases  are.  This  leads  to  the  question  : 
When  may  we  judge  two  probabilities  to  be  equal  ?  And  this  leads 
us  at  once  to  one  of  the  cruces  of  the  Theory  of  Probability,  viz., 
the  famous  Principle  of  Non-Sufficient  Reason,  or,  as  Mr.  Keynes 
prefers  to  call  it,  the  Principle  of  Indifference.  In  the  negative 
and  critical  part  of  this  chapter  Mr.  Keynes  found  most  of  the 
work  already  done  for  him  by  Von  Kries,  one  of  the  few  writers 
on  the  philosophical  side  of  probability  who  are  really  worth 
reading.  Von  Kries  had  already  pointed  out  the  absurd  results 
which  a  light-hearted  use  of  the  Principle  of  Indifference  had 
led  to.  He  did  indeed  attempt  to  base  on  these  a  positive  state- 
ment of  the  proper  limits  of  the  Principle ;  but  I  am  relieved 
to  notice  that  Mr.  Keynes  finds  the  precise  upshot  of  Von  Kries's 
positive  theory  as  hard  to  grasp  as  I  have  always  done  myself. 

By  studying  the  cases  where  the  uncritical  use  of  the  Principle 
of  Indifference  ends  in  absurdities  Mr.  Keynes  elicits  the  following 
conditions  which  must  be  fulfilled  if  it  is  to  be  applicable.  (1)  The 
various  alternatives  under  consideration  must  be  capable  of  being 
put  into  the  same  form,  i.e.,  they  must  simply  be  different  instances 
of  a  single  prepositional  function  <£.  This  cuts  out  the  wild  ap- 
plications of  the  Principle  to  pairs  of  contradictory  alternatives  in 
which  Jevons  habitually  indulged.  The  two  alternatives  "  x  is 
red "  and  "  x  is  not  red "  are  not  of  the  same  form.  The  first 
means  that  x  has  the  colour  red.  The  second  certainly  does  not 
mean  that  x  has  the  colour  "  non-red,"  for  non-red  is  not  a  colour. 
(2)  The  alternatives  must  not  be  sub-divisible  into  other  alternatives 
of  the  same  form  as  themselves.  Given  that  x  is  an  inhabitant  of 
Europe  it  follows  that  he  lives  either  in  Great  Britain  or  in  France 
or  in  Germany  or.  .  .  .  These  alternatives  are  of  the  same  form, 
and  so  far  all  is  well.  But  each  of  them  is  divisible  into  sub- 
alternatives  of  the  same  form  as  itself.  The  alternative  that  x 
lives  in  Great  Britian  is  divisible  into  such  alternatives  as  that  he 
lives  in  England,  that  he  lives  in  Scotland,  etc.  .  ..  It  is  by  ignor- 
ing this  condition  that  mathematicians  who  treat  of  geometrical 
probability  so  often  reach  different  solutions  of  the  same  problem. 

Subject  to  these  two  conditions  Mr.  Keynes  states  the  Principle 


j.  M.  KEYNES,  A  Treatise  on  Probability.  77 

as  follows.  The  alternatives  <£(&)  and  (f>(b)  are  equally  probable 
with  respect  to  the  data  h,  provided  that  h  can  be  written  in  the 
form /(a)  f(b)  h',  where  f(a)  and  /(&)  are  logically  independent,  h' 
is  absolutely  irrelevant  to  both  alternatives,  and/(&)  and  f(b)  are 
the  only  parts  of  h  that  are  relevant  to  <£(a)  and  <£(&)  respectively. 
(There  is  a  puzzling  mistake  in  Mr.  Keynes's  symbolism  on  p.  60, 
§  21.  He  says :  "  It  might  be  the  case  that  .  .  .  <f>(x)  =  x  is  the 
only  prepositional  function  common  to  all  of  them  "  (i.e.,  the 
alternatives).  He  cannot  possibly  mean  this,  for  it  is  sheer  non- 
sense that  <f>(x)  which  is  a  proposition  about  x  should  ever  be 
identical  with  x  itself.  What  he  really  means  is  simply  that  <j>(x) 
might  be  nothing  but  x  =  a.v.x  =  b.v.x^c.\.  .  .  .  where  a  ,b,  c, 
.  .  .  are  just  proper  names  or  other  designations  of  the  altern  tives. 
Such  a  <£  will  not  do.  His  re  1  point  therefore  is  that  the  alterna- 
tives must  be  members  of  a  class  which  is  denned  intensively,  and 
not  by  a  mere  enumeration  of  its  members.) 

It  will  be  seen  then  that  all  judgments  of  indifference  involve 
judgments  of  irrelevance.  We  have  to  know  what  part  of  h  is 
irrelevant  to  both  <£(a)  and  </>(&)  before  we  can  see  whether  h  does 
fall  into  the  form  required  for  the  Principle  of  Indifference.  These 
judgments  of  irrelevance  are  of  fundamental  importance  in 
Probability,  and  no  rules  can  be  given  for  making  them.  In  the 
end  we  h  ive  to  come  down  to  direct  insight,  just  as  we  have  to 
do  in  the  end  in  judging  the  validity  of  any  deductive  argument. 

Mr.  Keynes  makes  one  very  important  observation  here  on  the 
dangers  of  symbolism.  So  long  as  we  are  dealing  with  mere  a's 
and  b's  all  that  we  know  about  them  is  that  they  are  both  instances 
of  some  (j>.  Jiut  the  moment  you  substitute  something  definite, 
like  Socrates,  for  a,  and  something  else  definite,  like  Plato,  for  &, 
you  can  no  longer  assume  that  the  conditions  for  the  Principle  of 
Indifference  still  hold.  The  moment  you  know,  not  merely  that 
you  are  dealing  with  a  <£,  but  also  know  which  particular  one  of 
the  </>'s  you  are  dealing  with,  you  may  have  fresh  relevant  in- 
formation. 

Having  treated  the  conditions  under  which  two  or  more  pro- 
babilities may  be  judged  to  be  equal  Mr.  Keynes  turns  to  the 
question  :  "  Under  what  conditions  can  one  probability  be  judged 
to  be  greater  or  less  than  another?  "  Such  comparisons  can  only 
be  made  directly  \\hen  either  (a)  we  have  the  same  data,  and  one 
of  the  propositions  whose  probability  is  sought  is  a  conjunctive 
containing  the  other  proposition  as  a  part ;  or  (b)  when  the  pro- 
position whose  probability  is  sought  is  the  same  in  both  cases,  but 
the  datum  in  one  is  a  conjunctive  which  includes  the  data  of  the 
other  as  a  part.  Into  the  exact  refinements  that  are  needed  here 
I  will  not  enter.  Mr.  Keynes  shows  that,  by  combining  cases  (a) 
and  (b),  we  can  sometimes  indirectly  compare  probabilities  which 
do  not  fall  under  either  rubric. 

(2)  The  prolegomena  to  the  measurement  of  probability  are  now 
completed,  and  we  can  turn  to  another  most  important  question 


78  CEITICAL  NOTICES: 


already  been  mentioned.  If  there  is  nothing  to  choose  in 
point  of  correctness  between  the  probabilities  of  a  proposition  with 
respect  to  a  wider  and  to  a  narrower  set  of  data  why  do  we  prefer  the 
former  probability  to  the  latter  ?  Why  do  we  attach  more  weight 
to  the  low  probability  of  the  patient  who  is  known  to  have  taken 
both  arsenic  and  an  emetic  dying  in  the  next  half  hour  than  to  the 
much  higher  and  equally  correct  probability  of  the  same  event 
relative  to  the  narrower  data  that  he  has  taken  arsenic?  This 
extremely  puzzling  question  is  attacked  by  Mr.  Keynes  in  a  chapter 
on  the  Weight  of  Arguments.  I  do  not  know  of  any  other  writer 
who  has  raised  it  except  myself  in  the  chapter  on  Causation  in 
Perception,  Physics,  and  Reality  ;  though  I  do  not  doubt  that  Mr. 
Johnson  has  an  elaborate  treatment  of  it  up  his  sleeve.  Roughly 
speaking,  any  increase  in  the  amount  of  relevant  evidence  increases 
the  weight  of  an  argument,  though  it  may  leave  the  probability 
unchanged  or  may  decrease  it.  We  have  already  seen  an  example 
of  the  latter  ;  let  us  now  consider  the  former.  Suppose  we  start 
with  a  probability  a/h.  A  new  piece  of  evidence  k  may  arise,  and 
k  may  consist  of  two  parts  k^  and  k2,  one  of  which  is  favourably 
and  the  other  unfavourably  relevant  to  a/h.  In  that  case  it  is 
possible  that  a/hk  =  a/h.  Nevertheless  the  weight  of  a/hk  is 
greater  than  that  of  a/h.  Mr.  Keynes  discusses  various  cases  in 
which  weights  can  be  compared;  and  he  considers  the  relation 
between  weight  and  what  is  called  "  probable  error"  in  statistics. 
In  general  a  big  probable  error  is  a  sign  of  scanty  observations, 
and  therefore  of  a  low  weight  for  one's  result.  But  this  correlation 
is  not  absolutely  invariable.  I  wish  that  Mr.  Keynes  had  discussed 
why  we  feel  it  rational  to  prefer  an  argument  of  greater  weight  to 
one  of  less  weight.  I  think  that  our  preference  must  be  bound  up 
in  some  way  with  the  notion  that  to  every  event  there  is  a  finite 
set  of  conditions  relative  to  which  the  event  is  certain  to  happen  or 
certain  not  to  happen.  So  long  as  the  evidence  is  scanty  a  high 
probability  with  respect  to  it  does  not  make  it  reasonable  to  act  as 
if  we  knew  that  the  event  would  happen,  because  it  is  reasonable 
to  suppose  thit  we  have  only  got  hold  of  a  very  small  selection  of 
the  total  conditions  and  that  the  missing  ones  may  be  such  as  to 
be  strongly  relevant  in  an  unfavourable  direction.  If  the  proba- 
bility remains  high  relative  to  a  nearly  exhaustive  set  of  data  we 
feel  that  there  is  less  danger  that  the  missing  data  may  act  in  the 
opposite  direction.  In  fact,  what  we  assume  is  that  a  high 
probability  with  respect  to  a  wide  set  of  data  is  a  sign  of  certainty 
with  respect  to  the  complete  set  of  relevant  data. 

This  exhausts  the  main  features  of  Part  I.  Part  II.  is  largely 
the  formal  development  of  the  fundamental  axioms  of  probability. 
Much  of  it  could  be  accepted  by  a  person  who  rejected  Mr  Keynes's 
view  as  to  what  probability  really  is.  The  most  exciting  theorems 
in  this  part  are  due  to  Mr.  Johnson,  whose  valuable  conception  of 
"  Coefficients  of  Dependence  "  is  introduced  and  explained.  It  is 
worth  while  to  mention  a  very  plausible  fallacy  in  probable  reason- 


j.  M.  KEYNES,  A  Treatise  on  Probability.  79 

ing  which  is  detected  and  dealt  with  mathematically  by  Mr. 
Johnson's  methods.  It  seems  plausible  to  hold  that  if  k  is 
favourably  relevant  to  m/h  and  m  is  favourably  relevant  to  x/h 
then  k  must  be  favourably  relevant  to  x/h.  It  is  shown  here  that 
this  is  not  in  general  true;  and  the  two  conditions  under  which 
alone  it  is  true  are  elicited.  It  is  fairly  easy  to  illustrate  part  at 
least  of  this  fallacy  by  an  example.  The  fact  that  a  man  is  a 
-doctor  increases  the  probability  that  he  will  have  visited  smallpox 
patients,  and  the  fact  that  a  person  has  visited  smallpox  patients 
increases  the  probability  that  he  will  get  smallpox.  It  by  no 
means  follows  that  the  fact  that  a  man  is  a  doctor  increases  the 
probability  that  he  will  get  smallpox.  For  this  fact  also  increases 
the  probability  that  he  is  properly  vaccinated  and  that  he  will  take 
reasonable  precautions.  And  this  of  course  decreases  the  prob- 
ability that  he  will  get  smallpox.  Thus  we  see  that  it  is  not 
enough  that  k  shall  be  favourably  relevant  to  something  that  is 
favourably  relevant  to  x.  It  is  also  necesslary  that  k  shall  not  be 
favourably  relevant  to  anything  that  is  unfavourably  relevant  to 
x.  The  second  condition  is  more  subtle,  and  I  cannot  at  the 
moment  think  of  any  simple  example  that  would  illustrate  it.  As 
an  example  of  the  power  of  the  Keynes-Johnson  methods  the 
reader  is  advised  to  look  at  Chapter  XVII.,  in  which  Mr.  Keynes 
solves  in  a  few  lines  problems  over  which  Boole  spent  pages  of 
.algebra,  arriving  as  often  as  not  at  results  which  are  certainly 
wrong. 

To  the  mathematician  I  should  imagine  that  the  most  interest- 
ing thing  in  this  part  would  be  Mr.  Keynes's  beautiful  treatment 
of  Laws  of  Error,  and  his  general  solution  of  the  problem :  What 
form  must  the  law  of  error  take  in  order  that  the  most  probable 
value  of  a  measured  variable  shall  be  represented  by  the  arithmetic, 
the  geometric,  the  harmonic,  and  other  means,  of  the  observed 
values  ?  I  know  of  no  treatment  of  this  subject  which  approaches 
Mr.  Keynes's  for  clearness  and  generality.  To  most  readers  of 
MIND,  however,  the  chapters  of  greatest  interest  will  be  the  earlier 
ones  on  the  notions  of  Groups  and  Requirement. 

Both  these  notions  were  first  devised  by  Mr.  Johnson  to  deal 
with  such  problems  in  deductive  reasoning  as  are  raised  by  Mill's 
attack  on  the  Syllogism  and  by  the  apparent  paradox  about  a  false 
proposition  implying  all  propositions  and  a  true  proposition  being 
implied  by  all  propositions.  Mr.  Keynes  first  explains  the  applica- 
tions of  the  theory,  and  then  proceeds  to  give  his  own  extension  of 
it  to  the  case  of  probable  reasoning. 

A  group,  so  far  as  I  can  understand,  consists  of  a  set  of  pro- 
positions which  must  contain  some  formal  principles  of  inference, 
and  includes  in  addition  all  propositions  that  follow  from  the 
fundamental  set  by  the  principles  which  are  contained  in  that  set. 
A  group  is  said  to  be  real  if  the  set  of  propositions  which  determine 
it  are  all  known  to  be  true,  otherwise  it  is  said  to  be  hypothetical. 
It  is  of  course  possible  for  the  same  group  to  be  determined  by 


80  CEITICAL   NOTICES  : 

several  alternative  sets  of  propositions,  though  a  given  set  neces- 
sarily determines  a  single  group.  Mr.  Keynes  and  Mr.  Johnson 
are  both  persuaded  of  the  extreme  importance  of  the  theory  of 
groups  in  the  logic  of  inference.  I  agree  with  them  to  this  extent, 
that  the  facts  that  the  theory  of  groups  takes  into  account  are  of 
vital  importance.  But  it  does  seem  to  me  that  they  can  all  be 
stated  much  more  simply  in  other  terms ;  and  I  have  failed  to  find 
anything  specially  important  that  follows  from  the  group  notation 
and  would  not  have  been  discovered  without  it.  Possibly  I  am 
only  exhibiting  my  ignorance.  The  essential  point  that  the  group 
theory  is  meant  to  bring  out  is  the  distinction  between  what 
Johnson  calls  the  Logical  and  the  Epistemic  factors  in  infer- 
ence. The  latter  is  the  question  of  the  order  in  which  we  get  our 
knowledge.  E.g.,  p  implies  q  provided  that  either  p  is  false  or 
q  is  true.  So  far  it  is  irrelevant  how  we  came  to  know  that  this 
disjunction  holds.  But  when  we  say  "if  p  then  q"  we  mean 
something  more  than  this.  We  mean  that  it  is  possible  to  know 
that  p  is  false  or  q  is  true  without  having  to  know  that  p  is  false 
or  having  to  know  that  q  is  true.  And  the  only  way  in  which  we 
can  know  such  a  thing  is  by  seeing  that  the  disjunction  is  an  in- 
stance of  some  formally  true  hypothetical  such  as  "if  SaP  then 
P&S  ".  Again,  if  we  want  to  infer  q  from  p  it  is  obviously  necessary 
to  be  able  to  know  that  p  is  false  or  q  true  before  you  know  whether 
q  is  true  or  not.  All  this  can  be  and  is  expressed  by  Mr.  Keynes 
in  terms  of  the  theory  of  groups ;  and  my  only  doubt  is  whether 
it  becomes  any  clearer  or  leads  to  anything  further  when  so  ex- 
pressed. 

A  proposition  has  a  probability  with  respect  to  a  set  of  data  h 
when  neither  it  nor  its  contradictory  falls  into  the  group  determined 
by  h.  Does  this  really  enlighten  us  any  more  than  to  know  (what 
is  equivalent  to  it)  that  neither  the  proposition  nor  its  contradictory 
must  follow  logically  from  the  premises  mentioned  in  h  by  the 
known  formal  principles  of  d  eductive  logic  ?  On  page  131  Mr.  Keynes- 
has  a  formidable  definition  in  terms  of  groups  of  the  statement 
that  "  the  probability  of  p  does  not  require  q  within  the  group  de- 
termined by  h".  When  this  definition  is  unpacked  it  seems  to  me 
to  amount  to  no  more  than  this :  You  can  make  a  selection  In!  cut 
of  h  such  that  no  part  of  h  outside  h'  will  alter  the  probability 
p/h'  when  added  to  h' ;  and  some  part  of  h  outside  h'  when  added  to 
h'  will  alter  the  probability  of  q/h'.  If  this  be  the  right  interpretation, 
it  is  far  easier  to  grasp  than  Mr.  Keynes's  definition  in  terms  of 
groups. 

Not  only  am  I  doubtful  of  the  fruitfulness  of  the  group  theory, 
I  am  also  not  satisfied  that  Mr.  Keynes's  treatment  ot  hypothetical 
groups  is  adequate.  All  groups  must,  so  far  as  I  can  see,  include 
in  their  fundamental  set  formal  principles  of  inference  as  well  a& 
premises.  I  quite  understand  that  the  premises  may  be  hypothet- 
ical. But  can  we  really  allow  the  generating  principles  to  be 
hypothetical  also  ?  Mr.  Keynes  does  not  discuss  this  point,  which 


j.  M.  KEYNES,  A  Treatise  on  Probability.  81 

seems  to  me  to  be  a  very  important  one  for  a  person  who  is  going 
to  admit  hypothetical  groups. 

Let  us  next  turn  to  Mr.  Keynes's  theory  of  inductive  generalisation, 
which  is  contained  in  Part  III.  It  is  peculiarly  gratifying  to  me 
to  find  how  nearly  Mr.  Keynes's  view  of  the  nature  and  limits  of 
induction  agrees  with  that  put  forward  quite  independently  by  me 
in  two  articles  in  MIND.  We  both  agree  that  induction  cannot 
hope  to  arrive  at  anything  more  than  probable  conclusions,  and 
that  therefore  the  logical  principles  of  induction  must  be  the  laws 
of  probability.  We  both  agree  that,  if  induction  as  applied  to 
nature  is  to  lead  to  results  of  reasonably  high  probability,  nature 
must  fulfil  certain  conditions  which  there  is  no  logical  necessity  why 
it  should  fulfil.  Finally,  we  agree  as  to  the  nature  of  those  con- 
ditions, in  general  outline  at  any  rate.  In  some  way  the  amount 
of  ultimate  variety  in  nature  must  be  limited,  if  induction  is  to  be 
practically  valuable ;  the  infinite  variety  of  nature,  as  we  perceive 
it,  must  rest  on  combinations  of  a  comparatively  few  ultimate 
differences.  But  of  course  Mr.  Keynes's  theory  is  far  more  de- 
tailed and  subtle  than  anything  of  which  I  am  capable  ;  and  it  is, 
so  far  as  I  know,  the  only  account  of  the  logic  of  this  process 
which  a  self-respecting  logician  can  read  with  any  satisfaction. 

The  problem  of  induction  boils  down  to  this :  We  examine  n 
things.  They  have  the  r  properties  jt^  .  .  .  pr  in  common;  this  is 
called  their  total  positive  analogy.  There  is  also  a  set  of  proper- 
ties ql  ...  qs  such  that  each  is  present  in  some  of  the  things  and 
none  is  present  in  all  of  them  ;  this  is  called  the  total  negative 
analogy.  Both  the  positive  and  the  negative  analogies  in  any 
actual  case  are  pretty  certain  to  be  greater  than  the  known  positive 
and  negative  analogies,  which  form  the  only  basis  of  our  argument. 
Our  object  is  to  prove  some  proposition  of  the  form  that  everything 
which  has  the  properties  p1  .  .  .  pm  has  the  properties  pr_t  .  .  .  pr. 
It  is  obvious  that  this  can  only  be  possible  if  some  part  of  the 
known  analogy  is  irrelevant.  E.g.,  all  the  examined  instances 
agree  in  the  fact  that  we  have  examined  them,  that  they  are  con- 
fined to  certain  limits  of  space  and  time,  and  differ  from  all  unex- 
amined  instances  in  these  respects.  Whenever  this  part  of  the 
known  analogy  is  relevant  to  the  attempted  generalisation,  it  is 
clear  that  the  attempt  is  doomed  to  fail.  Thus  an  essential  factor, 
in  all  inductive  generalisations  is  judgments  of  irrelevance.  Many 
of  them  no  doubt  depend  on  past  experience,  but  Mr.  Keynes  holds 
that  there  must  be  a  residuum  which  is  a  priori.  The  only  im- 
portance of  the  Uniformity  of  Nature  is  that  it  is  a  general  prin- 
ciple of  irrelevance,  which  asserts  that  mere  differences  of  date 
and  position  are  irrelevant.  Mr.  Keynes  raises  the  question  in  a 
note  whether  this  is  affected  by  the  Theory  of  Eelativity ;  but  he 
does  not  answer  his  own  question.  However  this  may  be,  it  seems 
to  me  that  the  Uniformity  of  Nature,  thus  defined,  is  a  mere  pious 
platitude  ;  since — whether  space  and  time  be  absolute  or  relative — 
no  two  objects  or  events  ever  do  differ  merely  in  date  or  place. 

6 


82  CRITICAL  NOTICES  : 

Such  differences  always  involve  their  being  in  intimate  spatio- 
temporal  relations  with  different  sets  of  objects  or  events,  and 
these  differences  cannot  be  assumed  to  be  irrelevant. 

Our  generalisation  always  refers  to  much  less  than  the  known 
positive  analogy.  When  we  argue  that  all  swans  are  white  our 
generalisation  only  concerns  whiteness  and  those  few  properties 
by  which  we  define  a  swan.  But  all  the  examined  swans  were 
known  to  have  many  other  common  properties  beside  these,  and 
we  do  not  know  that  these  are  all  irrelevant.  All  that  we  posi- 
tively know  to  be  irrelevant  at  this  stage  is  the  properties  in  the 
known  negative  analogy.  We  can  reduce  the  dangers  thus  involved 
by  seeking  other  instances  which  increase  the  known  negative 
analogy.  For  this  purpose  mere  number  is  unimportant.  One 
instance  which  is  known  to  differ  from  the  previously  examined 
ones  in  many  of  those  properties  which  the  generalisation  assumes 
to  be  irrelevant  is  of  more  importance  than  dozens  of  instances 
which  are  exactly  like  those  already  examined.  But  there  remains 
a  danger  due  to  the  fact  that  the  total  analogy  is  almost  certain  to 
be  greater  than  the  knowrn  positive  analogy.  The  extra  and  un- 
known analogies  may  be  relevant;  and,  since  we  do  not  know 
what  they  are,  we  do  not  know  where  to  look  for  negative  analogies 
which  will  prove  them  to  be  irrelevant.  In  this  case  the  only 
course  is  to  increase  the  number  of  instances,  trusting  that,  even 
though  they  do  not  differ  in  any  known  respects  from  those  that 
have  already  been  examined,  they  will  probably  between  them 
differ  in  many  of  the  unknown  points  of  positive  analogy  from  the 
examined  instances.  All  this  however  only  tells  us  how  to  di- 
minish the  objections  to  an  inductive  generalisation.  It  does  not 
tell  us  that  any  inductive  generalisation  will  possess  a  reasonable 
degree  of  probability,  even  when  we  have  carried  out  these  pro- 
cesses to  the  utmost.  Something  more  is  clearly  needed  if  induc- 
tive generalisation  is  to  be  trustworthy. 

The  extra  factor  is  dealt  with  in  the  chapter  on  Pure  Induction. 
It  is  easy  to  prove  that  an  hypothesis  becomes  more  and  more 
probable  the  more  mutually  independent  consequences  of  it  are 
verified.  It  is  also  easy  to  prove  that,  if  it  starts  with  a  finite  pro- 
bability, sufficient  verification  of  mutuallyiindependent  consequences 
will  make  its  probability  approach  as  near  as  we  please  to  unity.  The 
problem  that  remains  is :  What  justifies  us  in  ascribing  a  finite  ante- 
cedent probability  to  any  inductive  generalisation  ?  To  this  Mr. 
Keynes  answers  that  we  are  only  justified  if  we  assume  that  all  the 
variety  of  perceptible  properties  springs  from  a  comparatively  small 
number  of  generating  properties. 

To  each  generating  property  there  corresponds  a  large  group 
of  perceptible  qualities,  but  we  must  admit  the  possibility  that 
the  class  of  perceptible  qualities  corresponding  to  <^  and  the 
class  corresponding  to  <j>2  may  partially  overlap.  If  so  the  group 
common  to  the  two  will  not  tie  us  down  to  a  single  generator. 
Setting  this  possibility  aside  for  the  moment,  we  see  that  if  a 


J.  M.  KEYNES,  A  Treatise  on  Probability.  83 

group  a  of  perceptible  qualities  is  found  to  be  accompanied  by 
a  group  ft  there  is  a  finite  probability  that  the  complete  group 
a/2  corresponds  to  a  single  generator,  or  that  the  generators  of  a 
include  among  them  the  generators  of  /3.  If  this  is  so  a  will  not 
be  able  to  occur  without  J3,  and  there  is  thus  a  finite  antecedent 
probability  of  the  generalisation,  on  which  induction  can  build. 
If  we  allow  that  a  group  of  perceptible  qualities  may  have  a 
plurality  of  possible  generators  this  argument  breaks  down  ;  but 
if  we  assume  that  the  plurality  of  possible  generators  for  every 
set  is  finite  we  can  still  assign  a  finite  antecedent  probability 
to  inductive  correlations,  which  assert  that  the  next  S,  or  at  least 
a  certain  proportion  of  the  S's,  will  be  P. 

Mr.  Keynes  seems  to  me  to  be  right  here ;  and  it  is  true  that 
this  is  the  kind  of  assumption  that  does  lie  at  the  back  of  all  our 
scientific  reasoning.  I  have  only  two  remarks  to  make.  (1)  Does 
the  theory  of  generators  add  anything  to  the  facts?  Would  it 
not  be  enough  to  assume  that  perceptible  qualities  do  tend  to 
occur  in  bundles  ?  This  is  the  whole  cash- value  of  the  assump- 
tion, and  the  doctrine  of  generators  seems  to  be  nothing  more 
than  a  hypothetical  explanation  of  our  assumption.  (2)  Mr. 
Keynes  holds  that  there  is  no  circle  in  saying  both  that  no  in- 
ductive generalisation  can  acquire  a  finite  probability  without 
this  assumption,  and  that  the  results  of  induction  may  make 
this  assumption  progressively  more  and  more  probable. 

It  is  therefore  not  necessary  that  the  fundamental  inductive 
assumption  should  be  certain.  It  is  enough  if  it  ever  had  a  finite 
probability ;  for  all  subsequent  experience  has  tended  to  support  it. 
What  Mr.  Keynes  means  is,  I  think,  this :  If  the  world  is  a  system 
with  a  finite  number  of  generating  properties  we  might  expect  to 
find  a  good  deal  of  regularity  and  repetition  in  it.  Now,  up  to  the 
present,  we  have  found  more  and  more  regularity  and  repetition 
the  more  carefully  we  have  looked  for  them.  Thus  the  actual 
course  of  experience  has  been  such  as  to  increase  the  probability 
of  the  inductive  hypothesis,  provided  that  it  started  with  any  finite 
probability.  This  works  out  in  practice  to  the  result  that  a  large 
part  of  the  confidence  that  we  now  feel  in  any  inductive  general- 
isation is  due,  not  to  the  special  evidence  for  it,  but  to  the  enormous 
and  steadily  increasing  amount  of  regularity  that  we  have  found  in 
other  regions.  There  is,  I  think,  no  circle  in  this.  Thus  the  one 
fundamental  assumption  of  induction  is  that  we  can  know  some-  ,/ 
how  that  the  inductive  hypothesis  that  nature  is  fundamentally 
finite  has  a  finite  antecedent  probability.  Mr.  Keynes  admits  that 
it  is  very  difficult  to  see  how  we  can  know  this.  It  is  certainly 
not  an  a  priori  principle,  self  evident  for  all  possible  worlds,  that 
every  system  must  depend  on  a  finite  number  of  generators.  We 
can  only  suppose  that  in  some  way  we  can  see  directly  that  this 
has  a  finite  probability  for  the  actual  world.  But  the  epistemology 
of  this  is  at  present  wrapped  in  mystery. 

In  Part  IV.  many  interesting  problems  are   discussed  ;   but    I 


84  CRITICAL   NOTICES: 

must  only  glance  at  them.  Mr.  Keynes  ranges  from  Psychical 
Research  to  Principia  Ethica,  and  from  the  Argument  from  Design 
to  the  Petersburg  Problem  ;  and  he  has  something  illuminating 
to  say  about  all  of  them.  From  the  point  of  view  of  pure  proba- 
bility the  most  important  thing  in  this  part  is  the  definitions  of  an 
objectively  chance  event  and  of  a  random  selection.  The  former  is 
very  important  in  connexion  with  statistical  mechanics,  the  latter 
in  connexion  with  most  statistical  reasoning.  A  chance  event  is 
not  one  which  is  supposed  to  be  undetermined.  Nor  is  it  always 
one  whose  antecedent  probability  is  very  small.  To  throw  a  head 
with  a  penny  is  a  chance  event,  but  its  probability  is  -J.  An 
event  may  be  said  to  be  a  matter  of  chance  when  no  increase  in 
our  knowledge  of  the  laws  of  nature,  and  no  practicable  increase 
in  our  knowledge  of  the  facts  that  are  connected  with  it,  will 
appreciably  alter  its  probability  as  compared  with  that  of  its 
alternatives. 

Part  V.  deals  with  the  principles  of  statistical  inference.  It 
is  too  technical  for  me  to  give  any  complete  account  of  it,  so  I 
will  confine  myself  to  a  very  short  summary  of  the  most  im- 
portant points  in  it.  (1)  Mr.  Keynes  considers  the  conditions 
under  which  Bernoulli's  theorem  holds,  and  shows  that  they 
are  so  restricted  that  we  can  seldom  in  practice  count  on  their 
being  fulfilled.  (2)  He  severely  criticises  Laplace,  and  particularly 
his  famous  Eule  of  Succession.  This  occurs  in  connexion  with 
the  attempted  inversion  of  Bernoulli's  theorem.  I  agree  with 
Mr.  Keynes  about  this  rule,  but  it  seems  to  me  that  he  is  a 
little  unfair  to  it  in  one  respect.  He  assumes  that  it  always 
deals  with  cases  where  what  is  drawn  is  replaced  before  the 
next  drawing.  On  that  supposition  it  is  true,  as  he  points  out, 
that  the  formula  only  holds  as  the  number  of  drawings  tends  to 
infinity.  But  the  same  formulae  hold  without  this  restriction 
when  the  objects  drawn  are  not  replaced.  And  surely,  if  the 
Rule  claims  to  have  the  slightest  application  to  our  investigations 
of  nature,  the  latter  is  the  right  alternative.  For  we  cannot 
observe  the  same  event  twice  over,  any  more  than  we  can  draw 
a  counter  twice  out  of  a  bag  if  we  do  not  replace  it.  (3)  On 
all  these  subjects  Mr.  Keynes  prefers  Bortkiewicz,  Tschuproff, 
Tchebycheff,  and  Lexis  to  the  classical  French  school.  I  am 
afraid  that,  with  the  exception  of  Lexis,  these  names  are  mere 
sternutations  to  most  English  readers ;  but  I  suppose  we  may 
look  forward  to  a  time  when  no  logician  will  sleep  soundly  without 
a  Bortkiewicz  by  his  bedside.  (I  must  remark  in  passing  that 
the  beginning  of  Mr.  Keynes's  sketch  of  Tchebycheffs  theorem 
seems  to  the  uninitiated  to  commit  precisely  the  same  kind  of 
fallacy  which  Mr.  Keynes  himself  points  out  in  Maxwell's  de- 
duction of  the  law  for  the  distribution  of  molecular  velocities  in 
a  gas.  This  is  on  page  353,  where  it  is  said  that  "  the  probability 
that  the  sum  x  +  y  +  z  .  .  .  will  have  for  its  value  XK  +  y^  +  z* 
.  .  .  is  pK  g\  r^  .  .  .  ".  Surely  this  forgets  that  a  sum  of  this 


BERTRAND  RUSSELL,  The  Analysis  of  Mind.          85 

value  could  be  made  up  in  a  great  number  of  different  ways  by 
taking  suitably  chosen  values  of  the  variables.  Why  should  not 
%a  +  yp  +  Zy  -  .  .  have  the  same  value  as  x*  +  y^  +  z^  .  .  .  ? 
In  that  case  the  probability  will  be  much  greater  than  pK  q\  r^.  .  .) 
(4)  About  past  statisticians  Mr.  Keynes  makes  a  remark  which 
exactly  hits  the  nail.  They  never  have  clearly  distinguished 
between  the  problem  of  stating  the  correlations  which  occur  in 
the  observed  data,  and  the  problem  of  inferring  from  these  the 
correlations  of  unobserved  instances.  There  is  nothing  inductive 
about  the  former ;  but,  as  it  involves  considerable  difficulties, 
the  statistician  has  been  liable  to  suppose  that,  when  he  has 
solved  these,  all  is  over  except  the  shouting.  Thus  the  inductive 
theory  of  statistical  inference  practically  does  not  exist,  save  for 
beginnings  in  the  works  of  Lexis  and  Bortkiewicz.  These  be- 
ginnings Mr.  Keynes  describes  and  tries  to  extend. 

There  are  several  misprints  in  the  book  beside  those  that  are 
mentioned  in  the  list  of  errata.  On  page  170  the  various  kinds  of 
fe's  have  got  mixed  up  in  the  course  of  the  argument.  On  page  183 
it  is  said  that  "  we  require  a/ah2h2,"  when  we  really  want  ajah-ji^. 
On  page  207  substitute  <j>(z)  for  <£(#)  on  the  left-hand  side  of  the  equa- 
tion. In  the  formula  at  the  bottom  of  page  386  read/  for/  in  the 
second  f  ictor  of  both  numerator  and  denominator.  On  page  395  in 
the  first  line  after  the  equation  read  pl  for  the  second  p  in  the  line. 

I  can  only  conclude  by  congratulating  Mr.  Keynes  on  finding 
time,  amidst  so  many  public  duties,  to  complete  this  book,  and  the 
philosophical  public  on  getting  the  best  work  on  Probability  that 
they  are  likely  to  see  in  this  generation. 

C.  D.  BEOAD. 


The  Analysis  of  Mind.    By  BERTRAND  RUSSELL,  F.R.S.     London  : 
George  Allen  &  Unwin,  Ltd.,  1921.     Pp.  310. 

"  TRAVELLING,  whether  in  the  mental  or  the  physical  world,  is  a 
joy,  and  it  is  good  to  know  that,  in  the  mental  world  at  least,  there 
are  vast  countries  still  very  imperfectly  explored." 

Many  will  feel  that  in  those  words,  which  occur  early  in  his 
latest  book,  Mr.  Russell  has  aptly  summed  up  his  own  attitude  to 
philosophy.  For  there  has  seldom  been  a  bolder  traveller  in  those 
realms  than  Mr.  Russell,  and  seldom  one  who  had  more  power  to 
charm  his  readers  by  the  accounts  of  his  discoveries,  or  to  com- 
municate to  them  something  of  the  zest  he  himself  finds  in  such 
adventures.  Almost  every  successive  work  which  has  come  from 
his  pen  represents  a  new  voyage  of  discoveiy,  and  most  of  his 
readers  must  at  times  have  found  it  difficult  to  keep  track  of  his 
rapid  progress.  But  never  before,  I  think,  has  he  made  so  venture- 
some a  journey  as  the  present  one,  or  covered  in  his  survey  so 
large  a  stretch  of  country. 

We  have  already,  of  course,  had  preliminary  reports  of  this 


86  CEITICAL   NOTICES: 

latest  adventure.  The  theory  which  Mr.  Eussell  now  expounds 
more  fully  was  adumbrated  in  his  paper  of  two  years  ago  printed 
in  the  Aristotelian  Society's  Supplementary  Volume  II.,  and  in 
that  form  it  has  already  been  both  attacked  and  defended  in  the 
pages  of  MIND.  But  the  present  work  is  wider  in  its  scope ;  it  is 
an  outline,  at  least,  of  a  system  of  metaphysics ;  and  the  theory 
of  knowledge  which  formed  the  subject  of  the  Aristotelian  paper 
appears  here  as  only  a  part  of  the  larger  scheme.  Mr.  Eussell 
has  not  (so  far  as  I  can  see)  withdrawn  any  of  his  former  conten- 
tions, but  they  appear  in  rather  a  different  light  when  they  fall 
into  their  proper  place  in  the  whole.  It  seems  convenient,  there- 
fore, to  treat  the  previous  papers  as  being  entirely  swallowed 
up  in  this  new  work,  and  to  take  this  book  as  being  the  first 
complete  presentment  of  the  new  theory. 

Its  scope  and  its  conclusion  are  briefly  indicated  in  the  preface. 
Psychology,  under  the  influence  of  behaviourism,  has  steadily  been 
growing  more  materialistic;  but  at  the  same  time  physics  has 
developed  in  the  direction  of  making  matter  less  and  less  material. 
The  two  tendencies  seem  at  first  sight  inconsistent,  but  Mr.  Eussell 
believes  that  they  are  not  really  so.  "  The  view  that  seems  to  me 
to  reconcile  the  materialistic  tendency  of  psychology  with  the 
anti-materialistic  tendency  of  physics  is  the  view  of  William  James 
and  the  American  new  realists,  according  to  which  the  'stuff'  of 
the  world  is  neither  mental  nor  material,  but  a  '  neutral  stuff'  out 
of  which  both  are  constructed.  I  have  endeavoured  in  this  work 
to  develop  this  view  in  some  detail  as  regards  the  phenomena  with 
which  psychology  is  concerned." 

This  statement,  however,  scarcely  brings  out  fully  the  nature  of 
the  task  which  Mr.  Eussell  has  attempted.  His  book  may  be 
looked  at  from  several  different  points  of  view.  The  reader  is 
likely  to  be  struck  in  the  first  place  by  the  extent  of  Mr.  EusselPs 
debt  both  to  the  behaviourists  and  to  the  American  new  realists. 
The  first  few  lectures  are  chiefly  occupied  with  an  exposition  of 
their  views,  and  it  might  seem  almost  as  if  Mr.  Eussell  had  aban- 
doned some  of  his  most  characteristic  positions  and  were  confining 
himself  to  lending  to  these  new  theories  the  aid  of  his  unequalled 
gift  for  the  lucid  exposition  of  complicated  questions  of  philosophy. 
But  as  the  work  proceeds,  this  first  impression  is  seen  to  be  quite 
inadequate.  Mr.  Eussell  finds  it  convenient  to  start  from  the 
same  point  as  the  behaviourists,  but  it  is  not  long  before  his  path 
diverges  from  theirs ;  and  what  he  does  borrow  from  them  he  uses 
simply  as  material  for  a  very  individual  and  singularly  bold  piece 
of  construction. 

In  carrying  out  this  new  theory,  he  has  indeed,  as  he  tells  us 
early  in  the  book,  abandoned  a  number  of  doctrines  which  he 
previously  held.  But  it  would  be  a  misapprehension  to  see  in  this 
a  complete  volte-face ;  what  has  happened,  rather,  is  that  Mr. 
Eussell  has  developed  one  line  of  thought  which  has  already  ap- 
peared in  his  writings.  The  present  work  becomes  most  intelligible 


BERTEAKD  RUSSELL,  The  Analysis  of  Mind.  87 

if  it  is  regarded  as  the  application  to  a  new  material  of  the  method 
followed  in  Our  Knowledge  of  the  External  World.  The  object  of 
that  work  was  to  show  that  the  "  matter "  dealt  with  by  physics 
can  be  exhibited  as  a  construction  out  of  sense-data,  i.e.,  that  all 
the  laws  of  physics  can  be  stated  as  laws  of  connexion  between 
sense-data.  The  present  lectures  attempt  to  analyse  "  mind  "  in 
the  same  way;  and  the  conclusion  is  that  there  is  no  specific 
character  "consciousness"  which  is  of  the  essence  of  mind.  We 
say  that  "consciousness"  exists  when  there  occurs  a  certain  com- 
plex of  sensations  and  images  related  in  a  certain  way ;  the  whole 
phenomenon  is  analysable  into  these  sensations  and  images,  but  by 
themselves  they  have  nothing  "  conscious  "  about  them.  Thus 
we  end  by  analysing  the  subject,  and  all  mental  states  and  mental 
processes  into  sensations  and  images  variously  inter-related. 

As  I  have  already  said,  the  book  begins  with  an  outline  of  the 
behaviourist  attitude  to  psychological  problems.  It  then  proceeds 
to  discuss  various  particular  points,  showing  how  far  the  behaviour- 
ist treatment  will  carry  us  and  where  it  turns  out  to  be  inadequate. 
Desire  and  feeling  are  dealt  with,  and  the  conclusion  is  reached 
that  they  can  be  satisfactorily  denned  in  behaviourist  terms ;  they 
become,  that  is  to  say,  names  for  certain  causal  laws  of  our  actions. 
(This  is  not  entirely  true  of  conscious  desire,  but  the  additional 
elements  there  present  are  held  not  to  make  any  fundamental 
difference.)  Two  chapters  are  then  devoted  to  the  exposition  of 
two  conceptions  which  Mr.  Eussell  regards  as  of  first-rate  import- 
ance for  the  definition  of  psychology — mnemic  caiisation  and  a 
perspective. 

The  exposition  of  the  latter  notion,  and  of  the  related  notion 
of  a  biography,  is  substantially  the  same  as  that  given  in  Our 
Knowledge  of  the  External  World  and  in  Mysticism  and  Logic.  But 
as  Mr.  Russell  is  here  more  concerned  with  psychology  than  with 
physics,  biographies  are  given  a  somewhat  fuller  treatment,  par- 
ticularly in  the  chapter  on  "The  Definition  of  Perception".  It  is 
pointed  out  that  we  can  define  a  biography  without  leaving  the 
standpoint  of  physics — the  biography  to  which  a  sensation  belongs 
is  the  set  of  particulars  that  are  earlier  or  later  than,  or  simultan- 
eous with,  the  given  sensation  (assuming  in  accordance  with  the 
theory  of  relativity  that  there  are  only  local  times).  But  we  find 
that  there  are  certain  biographies  which  have  their  parts  connected 
together  not  only  by  time-relations,  but  also  by  relations  of  ^mnemie 
causation ;  these  are  the  biographies  of  living  beings. 

And  at  this  point  we  come  on  a  new  fact,  of  great  importance 
for  psychology.  It  is  not  the  case  that  all  the  particulars  of  which 
we  are  aware  can  be  collected  together  both  to  form  physical 
objects  and  to  form  perspectives.  There  are  certain  appearances, 
commonly  called  images,  which  cannot  be  fitted  into  the  physical 
world  and  so  belong  only  to  perspectives ;  in  other  words,  images  have 
a  passive  place  but  not  an  active  place.  The  existence  of  such  par- 
ticulars is  of  course  revealed  only  by  introspection  ;  and  it  is  denied 


88  CEITICAL  NOTICES: 

by  the  behaviourists.  But,  argues  Mr.  Eussell,  once  we  accept  his 
conclusion  as  to  the  nature  of  physical  objects,  we  see  that  "the 
physical  world  itself,  as  known,  is  infected  through  and  through 
with  subjectivity,"  and  so  introspection  need  not  be  specially  dis- 
trusted just  because  it  is  subjective.  Psychology  is  much  more  of 
an  independent  science  than  the  behaviourists  would  allow. 
Images,  however,  turn  out  to  be  the  only  peculiar  fact  which 
introspection  reveals ;  Mr.  Russell  accepts  many  of  the  other 
behaviourist  criticisms  of  the  introspective  process,  and  agrees 
that  it  gives  no  ground  for  asserting  the  existence  of  a  subject, 
of  mental  acts,  mental  states  or  any  of  the  other  specifically 
"  conscious "  entities  which  it  has  often  been  supposed  to  dis- 
close. 

So  far  then  we  have  empirical  evidence  for  the  existence  of  two 
kinds  of  things  only — sensations  and  images.  A  later  chapter 
goes  on  to  discuss  their  respective  natures.  The  conclusion  as 
regards  sensation  is  that  of  the  American  realists;  "a  patch  of 
colour  and  our  sensation  in  seeing  it  are  identical  ".  Sensations 
in  fact  "  are  what  is  common  to  the  mental  and  physical  worlds  ". 
Images  are  clearly  different  in  some  way  from  sensations ;  but  in 
the  end  it  turns  out  that  they  differ  not  in  their  intrinsic  natures, 
but  only  in  the  causal  laws  which  they  obey.  Images  may  have 
mnemic  causes  and  always  have  mnemic  effects ;  sensations  have 
only  physical  causes  though  they  may  have  mnemic  effects. 

It  remains  for  Mr.  Russell  to  show  that  the  analysis  of  mind 
which  he  has  suggested  is  confirmed  by  an  examination  of  the 
remaining  kinds  of  mental  processes.  He  has  already  argued 
that  desire,  pleasure,  pain  and  perception  can  be  completely  ex- 
plained as  complexes  of  sensations  and  images ;  knowledge,  think- 
ing, truth  and  falsehood  have  still  to  be  analysed  into  the  same 
elements.  This  task  is,  as  Mr.  Russell  recognises,  the  most  difficult 
part  of  the  enterprise;  and  it  occupies  nearly  the  whole  of  the 
second  half  of  the  volume. 

This  analysis  is  worked  out  on  the  lines  of  Mr.  Russell's 
Aristotelian  paper;  it  involves  considerable  complications  and  is 
scarcely  capable  of  being  summarised.  The  conclusion  is  that  a 
belief  consists  entirely  of  a  complex  of  sensations  and  images 
variously  related,  together  with  a  specific  belief-feeling ;  when  this 
complex  corresponds  in  a  certain  way  to  the  facts,  then  the  belief 
is  true,  and  we  have  knowledge.  There  is  no  such  thing  as  an 
immediate  cognitive  relation  :  "I  believe  knowing  to  be  a  very 
external  and  complicated  relation,  incapable  of  exact  definition, 
dependent  upon  causal  laws,  and  involving  no  more  unity  than 
there  is  between  a  signpost  and  the  town  to  which  it  points  ". 

"  The  concluding  chapter  collects  and  emphasises  the  general  con- 
clusions reached ;  attempts  to  define  mind,  which  however  is  found 
to  be  "  a  matter  of  degree,  chiefly  exemplified  in  number  and  com- 
plexity of  habits/'  and  so  not  capable  of  exact  definition ;  and  ends 
with  a  sketch  of  ''the  nature  of  that  fundamental  science  which  I 


BEETEAND  EUSSELL,  The  Analysis  of  Mind.  89 

believe  to  be  the  true  metaphysic,  in  which  mind  and  matter  alike 
-are  seen  to  be  constructed  out  of  a  neutral  stuff,  whose  causal  laws 
have  no  such  duality  as  that  of  psychology,  but  form  the  basis  upon 
which  both  physics  and  psychology  are  built ".  The  chapter  does 
not  profess  to  work  out  this  notion  in  detail,  but  only  to  suggest 
general  lines  on  which  it  might  be  worked  out.  The  above  funda- 
mental science,  Mr.  Eussell  thinks,  would  be  somewhat  nearer  to 
psychology  than  to  physics ;  at  least  physics  would  appear  as 
essentially  derivative. 

This  summary,  necessarily  very  inadequate,  will  still  I  hope  be 
sufficient  to  make  it  clear  that  the  new  theory  is  an  ambitious  one, 
and  that  in  boldness  of  construction  it  is  not  surpassed  by  anything 
that  Mr.  Russell  has  previously  done.  It  may  well  be  doubted 
whether  anyone  but  Mr.  Russell  would  have  had  the  courage  to 
attempt  even  the  outline  of  so  far-reaching  a  theory  within  the 
.limits  to  which  he  has  here  confined  himself.  And  even  those 
who  withhold  assent  from  the  conclusions  will  be  unable  to  withhold 
admiration  from  the  exposition. 

But  certainly  there  is  matter  and  to  spare  for  controversy  in  this 
volume.  The  criticisms  that  might  be  suggested  are,  I  think,  of 
two  kinds — those  directed  against  particular  points  in  Mr.  Russell's 
psychological  analysis,  and  those  attacking  the  tenability  of  his 
theory  as  a  general  account  of  the  nature  of  knowledge  and  of 
reality.  I  shall  mention  a  few  difficulties  that  occur  to  me  under 
each  of  these  heads. 

Mr.  Russell's  treatment  of  desire  is  an  excellent  example  of  his 
method.  Starting  from  the  behaviourist  point  of  view  he  concludes 
that  the  conscious  element  in  desire  is  of  secondary  importance  ; 
"  the  primitive  non-cognitive  element  .  .  .  seems  to  be  a  push,  not 
-a  pull,  an  impulsion  away  from  the  actual,  rather  than  an  attraction 
towards  the  ideal.  Certain  sensations  and  other  mental  occurrences 
have  a  property  which  we  call  discomfort ;  these  cause  such  bodily 
movements  as  are  likely  to  lead  to  their  cessation."  As  for  dis- 
comfort and  its  opposite,  pleasure,  "  we  may  regard  them  as 
separate  existing  items  in  those  who  experience  them,  or  we  may 
regard  them  as  intrinsic  qualities  of  sensations  and  other  mental 
occurrences,  or  we  may  regard  them  as  mere  names  for  the  causal 
characteristics  of  the  occurrences  which  are  uncomfortable  or 
pleasant  ".  Holding  that  there  is  nothing  conclusive  to  be  said  in 
favour  of  the  first  view,  Mr.  Russell  proceeds  to  argue  that,  since 
•either  the  second  or  the  third  is  equally  capable  of  accounting  for 
the  facts,  "  it  is  safer  to  avoid  the  assumption  that  there  are  such 
intrinsic  qualities  of  mental  occurrences  as  are  in  question,  and  to 
•assume  only  the  causal  differences  which  are  undeniable  ".  Dis- 
comfort, then,  like  desire  becomes  merely  a  name  for  a  causal  law 
of  our  actions  ;  and  Mr.  Russell  has  analysed  away  two  things 
which  might  have  been  held  to  have  something  specifically 
"  mental  "  about  them. 

What  Mr.  Russell  here  describes  as  ;:  avoiding  an  assumption  " 


90  CRITICAL  NOTICES: 

seems  to  me  to  pass  later  on  into  something  much  more  positive, 
but  I  leave  that  point  aside  for  the  moment.  My  difficulty  is  that 
the  suggested  definition  of  discomfort  does  not  seem  to  correspond, 
even  in  extension,  with  the  ordinary  use  of  the  word.  There  arer 
it  seems  to  me,  cases  of  what  would  he  described  (and  properly 
described)  as  discomfort  where  it  is  not  true  that  <l  the  occurrence 
in  question  stimulates  voluntary  or  reflex  movements  tending  to 
produce  some  more  or  less  definite  change  involving  the  cessation 
of  the  occurrence  " — as  when  a  person  has  lost  hope  of  improving 
his  condition.  A  man  suffering  from  a  mortal  illness  might  be  in 
such  a  state,  and  might  resign  himself  to  continued  discomfort  (and 
I  am  not  here  challenging  the  distinction  between  discomfort  and 
pain).  There  are  equally  I  think  cases  where  a  behaviour-cycle, 
^involving  consciousness  of  the  end,  is  in  progress,  but  where 
discomfort,  in  anything  like  the  ordinary  sense  of  the  word,  is 
absent — as  when  a  man  is  eagerly  engaged  in  playing  some  game.. 
The  question  then  of  what  discomfort  really  is  cannot  be  shelved  by 
proposing  to  define  it  as  Mr.  Eussell  does.  Introspection,  it  seems 
to  me,  shows  it  to  be  a  positive  mental  fact  of  some  kind ;  and  this, 
if  it  is  true,  is  surely  of  more  importance  than  the  question  whether 
we  can  "  get  on  "  without  it  or  not.  We  can  get  along  somehow 
without  images,  if  it  comes  to  that ;  but  Mr.  Eussell  admits  their 
existence,  for  no  more  complicated  reason  than  that  he  can  see 
quite  clearly  that  there  are  such  things. 

No  doubt,  however,  the  point  is  not  a  vital  one  for  Mr.  Russell's 
theory.  He  would  probably  be  ready  to  grant  that  pleasure  and 
discomfort  may  be  specific  "feelings,"  just  as  he  asserts  later  on 
that  belief  is  a  specific  feeling. 

The  question  of  the  nature  of  desire  remains  to  be  decided. 
The  primitive  element  in  desire,  Mr.  Eussell  says,  is  the  push  of 
discomfort ;  and  he  makes'this  statement  before  he  has  proposed 
his  own  definition  of  discomfort,  so  presumably  he  supposes  the 
statement  to  be  true  when  that  word  is  taken  in  its  everyday 
meaning.  I  cannot  feel  that  the  arguments  he  brings  forward 
here  are  really  convincing ;  he  does  not  seem  to  me  to  have  given 
enough  consideration  to  those  types  of  desire  which  are  most 
difficult  to  reconcile  with  his  view.  For  instance,  Sidgwick,  in  the 
passage  in  the  Methods  of  Ethics  where  he  touches  on  this  question, 
gives  a  careful  analysis  of  some  instances  of  desire,  and  reaches 
the  conclusion  that  in  those  instances  there  is  no  painfulness 
present;  there  is,  he  admits,  unrestfulness — but  unrestfulness  is 
not  the  same  as  uneasiness.  I  do  not  suggest,  of  course,  that 
Sidgwick  foresaw  the  coming  of  behaviourism  and  refuted  it  by 
anticipation ;  but  in  the  passage  in  question  he  seems  quite  alive 
to  the  force  of  some  of  the  points  which  have  struck  Mr.  Eussell, 
and  there  have  been  few  writers  who  could  weigh  a  question  of 
this  kind  more  judicially  than  Sidgwick.  Mr.  Eussell  might  say, 
of  course,  that  if  we  allow  for  the  effect  of  beliefs  in  causing- 
secondary  desires,  we  shall  be  able,  by  introducing  some  complica- 


BERTRAND  RUSSELL,  The  Analysis  of  Mind.  91 

tions,  to  bring  all  doubtful  cases  under  his  formula.     It  may  be 
so ;  but  I  confess  I  should  like  to  see  it  done. 

The  whole  point  is  of  course  a  minor  one  ;  and  no  doubt  alter- 
native analyses  of  desire  might  be  suggested  equally  compatible 
with  the  general  metaphysical  conclusion  of  the  book.  But  that 
conclusion  is  in  danger  so  long  as  a  single  type  of  mental  state 
resists  analysis  into  sensations  and  images,  even  if  all  the  others 
have  been  successfully  dealt  with. 

I  must  pass  on,  however,  to  what  Mr.  Eussell  says  about  theory 
of  knowledge,  for  it  is  here,  as  he  himself  recognises,  that  the  real 
testing-point  for  his  view  comes.  That  this  should  be  so  is  only 
natural  when  we  consider  that  Mr.  Russell's  view  is  in  one  respect 
the  latest  statement  of  a  doctrine  which  has  already  a  long  history 
behind  it,  viz.,  sensationalism.  Of  course,  Mr.  Eussell's  sensation- 
alism is  a  very  new  variety  of  that  old  philosophy,  but  I  think  it 
is  sufficiently  like  the  classic  type  to  make  the  application  of  the 
label  legitimate.  Again  and  again  the  positions  he  takes  up,  and 
almost  the  very  words  in  which  he  states  them,  recall  to  us  ir- 
resistibly similar  doctrines  in  Hume,  or  in  Mill,  or  in  Spinoza. 
Hume,  indeed,  is  definitely  quoted  on  more  than  one  occasion. 
And  no  one  can  help  feeling  that  the  whole  temper  of  the  work 
carries  on  the  naturalist  tradition.  The  latter  part  of  the  book, 
indeed,  deals  with  questions  which  are  already  classic  in  the 
history  of  discussion.  One  might  almost  say  that  here  Mr.  Eussell 
abandons  the  detached  position  which  he  has  previously  occupied 
with  regard  to  these  historic  controversies,  looking  on  both  sides  as 
being  equally  victims  of  some  misapprehension.  In  the  old 
dispute  between  naturalism  and  idealism,  he  is  now  definitely  on 
one  side.  (This  ought,  by  the  way,  to  be  a  very  welcome  event  to 
those  idealists  who  always  felt  that  the  new  realism,  since  it  was 
anti-idealist,  must  be  only  naturalism  in  a  new  guise.) 

No  apology,  I  think,  is  necessary  for  thus  treating  the  present 
work  as  a  document  in  the  history  of  philosophy.  It  is  not  only 
that  what  Mr.  Eussell  thinks  to-day  a  good  many  people  are  apt  to 
think  to-morrow  (although  they  may  find  that  by  that  time 
Mr.  Eussell  is  no  longer  in  agreement  with  them) ;  it  is  still  more 
that  the  support  of  one  with  Mr.  Eussell's  traditions  was  exactly 
what  the  new  naturalism  stood  most  in  need  of.  For  such  a 
theory  has  always  found  some  followers,  and  a  large  section  of 
psychologists  have  always  tended  towards  it  along  their  own  lines. 
But  since  the  success  of  the  neo-Kantian  attack  on  empiricism,  it 
has  been  generally  held  among  philosophers  that  whatever  partial 
truth  naturalism  might  contain  as  a  method  of  psychology,  its 
inadequacy  was  exposed  as  soon  as  it  attempted  a  logic  or  a  theory 
of  knowledge.  Now  it  is  precisely  in  the  region  of  logic  and  of 
theory  of  knowledge  that  most  of  Mr.  Eussell's  work  has  hitherto 
been  done.  This  new  alliance,  then,  seems  to  me  a  philosophical 
event  of  first-rate  importance. 

It  is  natural  to  ask,  as  Mr.  Joachim  has  already  done,  how  far 


9*2  CRITICAL   NOTICES: 

the  new  theory  can  escape  objections  such  as  Green  and  Bradley 
directed  against  the  older  sensationalism.  One  must  recognise 
however  that  Mr.  Russell's  position  is  considerably  more  subtle 
than  Hume's.  In  Hume  impressions  and  ideas  are  somehow 
conscious  states.  For  Mr.  Eussell  a  sensation  is  a  particular 
which  is  in  no  sense  mental ;  it  is  a  thing  which  may  enter  into 
consciousness,  but  it  has  no  essential  connexion  with  mind.1  But 
on  the  other  hand  Mr.  Eussell' s  position  is  more  subtle  than  that 
of  the  American  new  realists.  He  recognises  that  the  conscious- 
ness of  a  sensation  must  be  something  much  more  than  the 
occurrence  of  that  sensation.  Consciousness  must  be  of  some- 
thing ;  there  must  be  some  sort  of  duality  or  complexity  in  any 
conscious  event.  Nor  is  it  enough  that  there  should  be  a  sensation 
and  an  image  ;  there  must  be  a  belief-feeling  as  well.  Still  further, 
says  Mr.  Russell  (and  the  point,  if  not  the  words  in  which  it  is 
expressed,  might  almost  be  taken  from  some  neo-Kantian  criticism 
of  associationism),  "  it  is  not  enough  that  the  content  and  the 
belief-feeling  should  co-exist ;  it  is  necessary  that  there  should  be  a 
specific  relation  between  them,  of  the  sort  expressed  by  saying  that 
the  content  is  what  is  believed". 

The  theory  then  cannot  be  accused  of  too  great  naivete ;  Mr. 
Russell  is  perfectly  aware  that  what  seems  the  fundamental  fact  of 
consciousness — that  someone  is  conscious  of  something — has  got  to 
be  satisfactorily  explained.  The  question  is  whether  he  has  suc- 
ceeded in  showing  how,  by  adding  together  particulars  which  are 
themselves  only  objects,  we  can  reach  the  kind  of  complex  which 
seems  to  consist  in  a  subject  knowing  an  object. 

Now  a  large  number  of  people,  at  any  rate,  when  confronted 
with  a  theory  such  as  the  present  one  which  appears  to  succeed  in 
"  constructing  "  the  subject  in  this  way,  have  an  uneasy  feeling 
that  there  must  be  a  trick  somewhere — that  the  conclusion  seems 
plausible  only  because  a  subject  has  been  introduced  surreptitiously 
in  the  course  of  the  construction.  This  feeling  may  really  be  a 
sign  that  there  is  something  wrong,  since  it  is  certain  that  our  first 
perception  of  a  flaw  in  an  argument  is  often  a  vague  discontent  of 

'This  being  so,  would  it  not  have  been  better  to  discard  the  word 
<;  sensation  "  altogether  ?  Among  the  many  meanings  which  that  word 
has  had  in  philosophical  discussions,  it  has  always  at  least  meant  something 
more  or  less  connected  with  consciousness.  Mr,  Russell  would,  I  suppose, 
reply  that  the  thing  which  he  calls  a  sensation  is  the  same  thing  that  most 
people  call  a  sensation,  only  those  people  are  in  error  when  they  suppose 
that  the  thing  in  question  has  anything  mental  about  it ;  therefore  he  has 
a  perfect  right  to  retain  the  word  while  freeing  it  from  its  false  associa- 
tions. But  I  do  not  think  this  would  be  a  sufficient  answer.  For  people, 
when  they  call  a  thing  a  sensation,  mean  to  imply  that  it  is  mental  ;  and 
if  they  were  convinced  that  they  were  mistaken  in  supposing  it  to  be 
mental,  they  would  probably  say,  not  "  Well,  you  have  now  convinced 
me  that  sensations  are  not  mental,"  but  "  I  now  see  that  what  I  thought 
to  be  mental  is  really  not  so,  and  I  was  therefore  mistaken  in  calling  it  a 
sensation  ". 


BERTRAND  RUSSELL,  The  Analysis  of  Mind.          93 

this  kind  ;  it  may  on  the  other  hand  be  founded  on  a  mere  pre- 
judice, and  in  that  case  we  must  attempt  to  overcome  it  if  analysis 
discovers  no  justification  for  it ;  but  in  either  case  it  is  relevant  to 
register  its  presence. 

My  own  opinion  is  that  the  subject  really  is  introduced  in 
Mr.  Russell's  account  of  knowledge,  and  that  this  is  done  under 
cover  of  what  he  calls  the  "  belief- feeling  ".  The  "  belief -feeling  " 
is  of  capital  importance  in  his  analysis  ;  without  its  presence  there 
can  be  no  knowledge  and  no  consciousness.  It  is  strange  then 
that  anything  which  plays  so  large  a  part  in  the  theory  should 
receive  such  a  small  share  of  the  limelight.  And  yet  such  is  the 
case.  All  Mr.  Russell  tells  us  is  that  there  are  at  least  three  kinds 
of  belief,  memory,  expectation  and  assent,  and  that  each  of  these  is 
"  presumably  a  complex  sensation  demanding  analysis  ".  Some- 
times, as  in  this  passage,  he  calls  belief  a  sensation,  but  more  often 
he  calls  it  a  feeling ;  in  any  case  he  does  not,  he  says,  profess  to  be 
able  to  analyse  it.  But  short  of  analysing  it,  what  justification  is 
there  for  calling  it  a  sensation  or  a  feeling  and  thus  getting  it  to  fit 
into  the  general  formula  ?  If  we  are  to  talk  of  a  sensation  of 
belief,  surely  we  must  recognise  that  we  are  dealing  with  some- 
thing very  different  from  a  sensation  of  blue ;  for  the  essential 
characteristic  of  belief  is  that  it  is  directed  towards  something,  and 
it  is  only  by  the  possession  of  this  characteristic,  which  no  other 
sensation  appears  to  have,  that  it  is  capable  of  playing  in  know- 
ledge the  part  it  does  play.  I  do  not  see  how  we  can  be  satisfied 
with  the  statement  that  mind  can  be  analysed  exhaustively  into 
sensations  and  images  until  it  has  been  made  much  clearer  that 
belief  really  is  merely  a  sensation.  Nor  is  the  case  better  if  it  is 
spoken  of  as  a  feeling.  The  only  analysis  Mr.  Eussell  gives  us  of 
feelings  occurs  in  chapter  iv.,  and  there  as  we  have  seen  he  dis- 
tinguishes three  possible  theories  as  to  their  nature.  The  last  of 
these — that  a  feeling  consists  only  in  causal  properties — he 
definitely  rejects  in  the  case  of  belief ;  so  we  are  shut  up  to  the 
other  two,  and  of  those  Mr.  Russell  is  bound  to  choose  the  second, 
that  feelings  are  intrinsic  qualities  of  mental  occurrences.  Now  is 
it  plausible  to  say  that  belief  is  simply  a  quality  of  some  sensation 
or  image,  and  if  so  of  which  sensation  or  image  in  the  belief- 
complex  is  it  a  quality  ?  Not,  clearly,  of  any  one  of  the  images  of 
the  content,  for  the  belief  is  directed  towards  the  whole  content. 
Are  we  to  say,  then,  that  it  is  a  "  quality  "  of  some  organic  sen- 
sation, which  forms  a  part  of  the  belief-complex  (though  not  of  the 
content  believed)  ?  If  so,  is  it  at  all  intelligible  how  an  organic 
sensation  can  have  a  quality  which  has  the  peculiar  characteristic 
of  being  directed  towards  something  ?  Mr.  Russell's  whole  treat- 
ment of  feeling  is,  however,  inadequate ;  the  above  threefold 
division  of  theories  is  put  forward  originally  as  applying  only  to 
pleasure  and  discomfort,  but  later  on  in  the  book  we  are  referred 
to  this  chapter  for  the  analysis  of  feeling.  And  in  the  end,  Mr. 
Russell  wavers  between  calling  belief  a  feeling  and  calling  it  a 


94  CRITICAL   NOTICES  : 

sensation.  For  my  part,  until  the  "  belief-feeling "  has  been 
completely  analysed  and  turned  inside-out,  I  shall  continue  to 
believe  that  within  it  is  concealed  something  which  is  neither  a 
sensation  nor  an  image — something  which,  if  it  were  let  out  of  the 
bag,  would  upset  the  whole  construction. 

One  of  the  classical  objections  to  the  older  sensationalism  was 
that  it  led  inevitably  to  scepticism.  This  result  followed,  it  was 
held,  chiefly  because  sensationalism,  starting  with  nothing  but 
particulars,  could  never  reach  a  universal  proposition  by  any  valid 
process  of  inference.  As  regards  this  point,  Mr.  Russell's  position 
is  rather  peculiar.  "  I  think"  he  says  on  page  228,  "  a  logical 
argument  could  be  produced  to  show  that  universals  are  part  of 
the  structure  of  the  world,  but  they  are  an  inferred  part,  not  a  part 
of  our  data."  And  his  whole  way  of  speaking  in  that  chapter 
emphasises  the  view  that  the  way  in  which  we  know  universals  is 
even  more  indirect  than  the  way  in  which  we  know  other  things. 
When  we  are  "  thinking  of  a  universal  "  the  content  of  conscious- 
ness is  always  a  particular.  Of  course  there  is  always,  on  Mr. 
Russell's  view,  "  an  awkward  gulf "  between  content  and  object 
"  which  raises  difficulties  for  the  theory  of  knowledge  "  (at  least  he 
says  this  in  the  case  of  memory)  ;  but  the  gulf  would  seem  to  be 
greater  than  usual  in  the  case  of  universals,  for  in  their  case  the 
element  in  the  content  which  "  means  "  the  universal  is  never  itself 
a  universal.  "  A  universal,"  he  says,  "  never  appears  before  the 
mind  as  a  single  objecfc  in  the  sort  of  way  in  which  something 
perceived  appears  "  (p.  228).  (It  is  true  that  this  statement  is 
somewhat  difficult  to  reconcile  with  the  statement  on  page  274,  where 
speaking  of  an  image-proposition  about  the  position  of  a  door  and 
a  window,  he  says  "  In  the  case  we  have  just  been  considering  the 
objective  consists  of  two  parts  with  a  certain  relation  (that  of  left- 
to-right),  and  the  proposition  consists  of  images  of  these  parts  with 
the  very  same  relation  ".  I  do  not  know  whether  this  is  to  be  taken 
as  implying  that  there  are  some  universals  which  can  appear  before 
the  mind  as  single  objects ;  or  that  the  relation  in  this  case  is  not  a 
universal,  but  only  an  instance  of  a  universal.  However  that  may 
be,  the  view  that  only  particulars  can  appear  before  the  mind  is 
the  one  emphasised  in  most  passages  in  the  book.)  Now,  if  this  is 
so,  it  surely  does  raise  serious  difficulties,  not  indeed  as  to  the 
possibility  of  there  being  true  beliefs,  but  certainly  as  to  the 
possibility  of  there  being  reasoned  beliefs.  The  fact  that  one 
proposition  implies  another  can  never,  on  this  view,  be  directly 
perceived  ;  it  can  only  be  known  in  a  roundabout  manner.  I  need 
not  labour  the  point  about  the  difficulties  this  raises  as  to  the 
possibility  of  valid  inference  ;  and  I  do  not  suppose  for  a  moment 
that  Mr.  Russell  is  not  very  much  alive  to  it.  But  certainly  he 
does  little  to  remove  our  difficulties.  There  are  a  few  sentences  on 
pages  228-229,  outlining  the  way  in  which  the  logician  deals  with 
words  which  stand  for  universals,  but  they  are  clearly  not  intended 
to  do  more  than  glance  at  the  subject.  There  is  also,  in  the  lecture 


BERTRAND  RUSSELL,  The  Analysis  of  Mind.  95 

on  Truth  and  Falsehood,  a  section  devoted  to  verifiability  ;  but  the 
difficulties  there  discussed  are  such  as  arise  on  any  theory  of 
knowledge,  whether  it  admits  some  sort  of  immediate  awareness  or 
not.  Mr.  Eussell  has  scarcely  touched,  in  fact,  on  the  more  special 
•difficulties  which  beset  the  sensationalist  theory  of  knowledge  ;  and 
since  (as  I  have  already  said)  it  was  just  on  this  very  point  that 
his  aid  would  have  been  particularly  valuable,  one  feels  a  certain 
degree  of  disappointment  that  he  has  not  here  gone  more  fully  into 
the  matter. 

As  I  have  already  mentioned,  this  whole  work  is  an  application 
of  that  "  scientific  method  "  which  Mr.  Russell  first  outlined  for  us 
in  his  Lowell  Lectures.  He  does  not  indeed  state  this  fact  so 
explicitly  as  in  the  earlier  book  ;  but  the  nature  of  the  method  is 
made  clear  enough  at  particular  points  in  the  discussion.  At  such 
points  it  appears  how  vital  for  the  establishment  of  his  conclusions 
the  adoption  of  this  method  is.  It  may,  therefore,  be  not  irrelevant 
to  mention  a  few  objections  to  which  the  method  appears  to  me  to 
be  open. 

Its  most  characteristic  device  and  the  one  which  the  author  finds 
most  useful  for  his  purpose  is  that  which  we  have  already  seen 
employed  in  the  case  of  feeling,  viz.,  the  definition  of  a  thing  in 
terms  of  its  properties.  By  this  method  we  are  able,  when  the 
existence  of  anything  is  at  all  doubtful,  to  "  avoid  the  assumption  " 
of  its  existence  and  yet  proceed  successfully  with  our  construction. 
And  Mr.  Russell  has  left  the  path  along  which  he  proceeds  to  his 
goal  haunted  by  the  ghosts  of  such  possible  existences. 

Now  if  it  should  be  the  case — and  it  is  admitted  that  it  may  be 
the  case — that  these  things,  whose  existence  wre  have  refrained  from 
asserting,  actually  do  exist,  then  our  final  account  of  reality  will  be 
an  incomplete  one.  It  will  not,  so  far  as  it  goes,  be  false  ;  it  will 
be  an  accurate  account  of  the  nature  and  connexions  of  things 
other  than  the  things  in  question  ;  but  incomplete  it  certainly  will 
be.  Now  it  may  be  argued  that  it  is  better  to  assert  only  what  we 
are  sure  of  than  to  strive  after  completeness  (which  is  in  any  case 
unattainable)  by  asserting  what  is  doubtful.  And  no  doubt  this 
statement  is  an  unimpeachable  one  as  it  stands.  But  it  assumes — 
and  the  assumption  is  an  important  one — that  we  can  divide  all  the 
things  of  whose  reality  there  is  question  into  two  classes,  the 
undoubted  and  the  doubtful ;  and  that  having  done  this,  we  ought 
then  to  define  the  latter  in  terms  of  the  former,  and  so  refrain  from 
asserting  their  existence.  Mr.  Russell  seems  to  work  on  this 
assumption  throughout  the  present  book  ;  a  fact  which  I  find  the 
more  surprising  because  in  his  Lowell  Lectures  he  clearly  recog- 
nises that  only  a  vague  distinction  can  be  made  between  the 
undoubted  and  the  doubtful. 

Now  suppose  there  is  no  clear  division  between  the  two  classes, 
are  we,  in  order  to  avoid  the  risk  of  error,  to  reduce  to  the  lowest 
possible  limits  the  number  of  things  whose  existence  we  assert  ? 
It  is  always  in  our  power  to  do  this,  for  the  method  is  capable  of 


96  CRITICAL  NOTICES: 

quite  general  application  ;  we  can  take  any  kind  of  entity  and  define* 
it  as  the  class  of  its  properties.  Mr.  Eussell  does  not  himself 
reduce  his  assertions  to  the  minimum  number ;  for  he  asserts  the 
existence  of  images,  although  it  is  possible  to  get  on  without  this 
assertion.1  He  does  this,  of  course,  because  images  seem  to  him 
to  belong  to  the  class  of  undoubted  things.  But  in  face  of  the? 
fact  that  Prof.  Watson  and  a  number  of  his  followers  deny  the 
existence  of  images,  it  is  surely  very  questionable  whether  we  can- 
place  them  straight  off  in  the  undoubted  class.  And  just  as- 
Mr.  Eussell  finds  the  class  of  undoubted  things  to  be  a  larger 
class  than  does  Prof.  Watson,  so  there  are  others  who  find  it  to- 
be  a  larger  class  than  does  Mr.  Russell ;  there  are,  for  instance, 
people  who  believe  that  they  are  immediately  aware  of  the  exist- 
ence of  the  subject.  It  would  appear  then  that  the  line  between- 
undoubted  and  doubtful  is  not  easy  to  draw  ;  and  so  the  question 
suggested  a  few  lines  above  "  Are  we  to  reduce  to  the  lowest 
possible  limits  the  number  of  things  whose  existence  we  assert  ?  '" 
demands  an  answer. 

For  my  own  part,  I  believe  that  this  question  ought  to  be 
answered  in  the  negative,  and  that  if  we  are  to  employ  the 
scientific  method,  we  shall  have  to  supplement  it  by  the  use  of 
other  principles  as  well.  The  question  of  whether  we  are  to> 
include,  in  our  account  of  the  contents  of  reality,  such  things  as 
physical  objects,  or  feelings,  or  selves  will  have  to  be  determined 
by  balancing  a  number  of  considerations ;  we  shall  be  influenced  on 
the  one  hand  by  the  desire  not  to  assert  the  existence  of  anything 
whose  existence  is  extremely  doubtful,  on  the  other  hand  by  the 
desire  not  to  make  our  account  incomplete  by  omitting  anything 
whose  existence  is  probable.  The  determination  of  the  degree  of 
probability  of  the  existence  of  any  particular  thing  will  itself  of 
course  be  a  complicated  matter  and  will  depend  on  a  number  of 
different  factors.  I  do  not  profess  to  be  able  to  say  to  what  sort  of 
system  of  reality  the  application  of  such  a  method  would  lead  us  ; 
and  even  to  touch  on  the  matter  would  lead  me  too  far  from 
Mr.  Russell's  book.  But  I  may  illustrate  my  meaning  by  a 
reference  to  one  point  which  is  of  cardinal  importance  in  Mr. 
Russell's  theory — the  question  of  the  existence  of  the  subject. 

Mr.  Russell  repeats  on  this  point  the  arguments  of  Hume  and  of 
James — he  has  looked  for  the  subject  and  found  nothing  but 

1  It  seems  a  little  difficult  to  understand  why  Mr.  Russell  does  not  apply 
his  method  to  the  belief-feeling.  He  says  on  page  247  :  "  Now,  it  seems 
clear  that,  since  believing  and  considering  have  different  effects  if  one 
produces  bodily  movements  while  the  other  does  not,  there  must  be  some 
intrinsic  difference  between  believing  and  considering  ;  for  if  they  were 
precisely  similar,  their  effects  also  would  be  precisely  similar  ".  But  in 
whab  does  this  case  differ  from  that  of  discomfort,  which  was  defined  in 
terms  of  causal  properties  ?  It  is  true  that  Mr.  Russell  gives  other 
arguments  for  holding  that  belief  differs  intrinsically  from  consideration  ; 
but  the  above  argument  is  presented  as  valid  by  itself. 


BERTKAND  KUSSELL,  The  Analysis  of  Mind.          97 

objects.  Dr.  Schiller  has  already  replied  that  he  has  looked  for  it  in 
the  wrong  place ;  but  Dr.  Schiller  and  Mr.  Kussell  start  from  such 
different  points  of  view  that  to  contrast  their  positions  on  any  point 
of  detail  does  not,  perhaps,  help  us  very  much.  There  is,  however, 
another  philosopher  whose  position  is  'not  so  far  removed  from 
Mr.  Kussell's,  who  holds  that  we  have  some  sort  of  immediate 
consciousness  of  the  subject ;  I  mean  Prof.  Alexander.  Now 
for  Prof.  Alexander,  of  course,  the  consciousness  we  have  of  the 
subject  is  of  a  different  kind  from  the  consciousness  of  objects  ; 
and  doubtless  Mr.  Eussell  would  reply  to  him  as  he  has  done  to 
Dr.  Schiller,  that  he  recognises  only  one  way  of  acquiring  know- 
ledge, and  that  is  by  observation  ;  the  subject  can  either  be  observed 
or  it  cannot.  But  is  this  not  after  all  to  make  an  assumption  ? — 
the  assumption  that  all  things  that  are  known  are  known,  as  it 
were,  on  the  same  plane.  Now  whether  or  not  we  consider  the 
notion  of  "  enjoyment "  a  satisfactory  one,  it  is  surely  at  least 
possible  that  the  above  assumption  is  false  and  that  there  may  be 
different  ways  of  knowing  things.  And  if  this  be  granted,  then  to 
begin  one's  enquiry  by  refusing  to  look  for  reality  except  by 
"  contemplation  "  is  to  cut  oneself  off,  at  the  very  start,  from  a 
possible  source  of  knowledge. 

The  fact  then  that  we  cannot  observe  the  subject  as  we  do  a 
sensation  ought  not  to  be  used  in  order  to  rule  out  at  once  the 
assertions  of  all  those  who  contend  that  they  have  some  sort  of 
immediate  consciousness  of  a  subject.  There  is  some  evidence  then 
for  the  existence  of  the  subject ;  and  once  this  is  admitted,  then 
surely  the  fact  that  the  assumption  of  the  subject  enables  us  to 
avoid  many  difficulties  in  the  theory  of  knowledge  becomes 
relevant ;  it  is  one  thing  to  bring  in  an  entity  merely  in  order 
to  simplify  theory  of  knowledge,  it  is  another  thing  to  do  so  when 
there  is  already  some  independent  evidence  for  the  existence  of 
such  an  entity.  Even  if,  then,  it  is  theoretically  possible  to  get  on 
without  asserting  the  existence  of  the  subject,  it  may  very  well  be 
that  we  ought  none  the  less  to  assert  it.  We  shall  have  to  weigh 
the  risk  of  asserting  more  than  we  have  conclusive  evidence  for 
against  the  risk  of  making  our  account  of  reality  less  complete 
than  it  need  be  by  the  omission  of  a  thing  for  whose  existence 
there  is  some  evidence. 

J  t  would  be  indefensible,  at  this  time  of  day,  to  occupy  space  in 
MIND  by  enlarging  on  the  proposition  that  what  Mr.  Kussell  writes 
is  worth  reading.  This  must  be  my  excuse  for  having  devoted  the 
present  review  to  criticism  rather  than  to  appreciation  of  his  latest 
brilliant  contribution  to  philosophy.  In  most  of  what  I  have  said, 
my  complaint  has  been  that  he  has  scarcely  allowed  himself  room, 
in  the  work  before  us,  to  give  to  a  number  of  obscure  questions  the 
fulness  of  treatment  which  they  demand.  Let  us  hope  that 
Mr.  Kussell  will  shortly  indulge  himself — and  us — to  the  extent  of 
a  volume  more  on  the  scale  of  The  Principles  of  Mathematics. 

ALAN  DOBWABD. 


VII— NEW   BOOKS. 

Studies  in  Human  Nature.     By  J.  B.  BAILLIE.    London  :  G.  Bell  &  Sons, 
Ltd.,  1921.     Pp.  xii,  296.     15s. 

PROP.  BAILLIE'S  object  in  this  important  and  welcome  collection  of  essays  is 
to  study  certain  characters  of  human  nature  for  their  own  sakes,  and  with- 
out the  bias  which  interest  in  a  particular  theory  might  give.  But  his 
choice  of  topics  was  directed  by  an  interest  in  the  question  of  the  limita- 
tions of  the  intellectualistic  attitude  which  many  philosophers  adopt. 
What  does  an  unbiassed  examination  of  the  facts  of  human  nature  tell 
us  of  the  function  of  thought  in  human  life,  of  its  relation  to  the  other 
human  activities,  and  of  the  nature  of  its  object  ?  Setting  out  with  such 
a  problem,  Prof.  Baillie  would  naturally  be  led  to  a  series  of  studies  such 
as  those  in  the  present  volume. 

His  answer  is  on  the  whole  disintegrating  ;  though  the  chapter  on 
"Philosophy  in  Human  Nature  "  shows  that,  for  the  author,  philosophy 
has  an  extremely  important  function.  The  postulate  that  the  world  is 
rational  is  not  borne  out  either  by  the  success  of  any  single  philosopher, 
or  by  common  agreement  among  philosophers,  or  by  a  steady  development 
within  philosophy  itself.  The  implication  that  rationality  is  the  most 
important  and  desirable  phase  of  human  nature  is  contradicted  by  the 
facts  of  human  nature.  ''Human  life  is  not  a  scientific  enterprise,  nor 
the  universe  a  mere  riddle  for  philosophers  "  (11).  The  rationalistic  atti- 
tude toward  the  universe  characterises  only  a  small  number  of  men,  re- 
stricted within  narrow  limits  of  space  and  time,  having  their  habitat  just 
like  certain  types  of  fish  or  tree. 

This  view  is  confirmed  by  an  examination  of  thought  itself,  of  the 
language  and  concepts  which  are  thought's  instrument,  and  of  the  non- 
logical  factors  by  which  thought  is  guided  and  sustained.  Thinking  is  a 
human  process,  just  like  seeing  ;  and  just  as  seeing  is  conditioned  by  the 
nature  of  our  eyes,  so  thinking  is  conditioned  by  the  nature  of  our  intel- 
lect. Our  intellect  shows  itself  in  the  kind  of  language,  the  sort  of  con- 
cepts, we  construct  for  the  systematisation  of  reality  ;  and  if  cur  intellect 
were  different,  our  constructions  would  be  different.  In  this  result  Prof. 
Baillie  seems  to  be  perfectly  consistent.  The  argument  that  awareness 
which  involves  the  human  organism  is  conditioned  by  that  organism,  while 
denied  by  some,  is  often  accepted  as  self-evident.  It  appears  to  us  to  be 
a  very  complex  question,  involving  many  considerations.  But  if  it  is  to  be 
accepted  anywhere,  then  consistency  seems  to  involve  that  we  should 
accept  it  in  relation  to  thought.  Prof.  Baillie  remarks  that  the  processes 
leading  to  error  are  not  in  any  way  different  from  those  leading  to  truth, 
and  that  hence  the  results  cannot  differ  in  kind  in  the  two  cases.  As  a 
consequence,  reality  is  regarded  everywhere  as  intimately  bound  up  with 
man's  activities.  There  is  no  reality  external  to  man  for  man  to  know  ; 
and  thus  knowing  is  not  an  attempt  to  get  into  touch  with  the  nature  of 
something  whose  nature  is  independent  of  man.  Knowing  becomes  an 
attempt  on  the  part  of  man  to  find  satisfaction  through  the  activity  of  one 
aspect  of  himself.  Truth  is  anthropomorphic. 


NEW  BOOKS.  99 

This  is  not  all.  If  ib  were,  it  could  still  be  maintained  that  knowing 
is  man's  central  activity,  and  that  systematic  completeness  of  knowledge 
is  the  goil  of  the  process.  Prof.  Baillie  denies  this.  Knowing  is  con- 
ditioned by  certain  non-logical  factors — emotion,  memory,  and  imagination 
are  the  chief — which  restrict  its  activities  and  determine  its  essential 
function.  Whether  the  intellect  shall  be  active  or  not,  in  what  directions 
it  shall  work,  how  far  its  activities  shall  go,  depend  on  the  emotional  re- 
sponse to  the  environment,  on  the  accuracy  and  width  of  memory,  on  the 
imaginative  penetration,  of  the  searcher ;  and  these  things  differ  with 
different  men.  Prof.  Baillie  would  conclude,  not  that  the  existence  of  the 
search  shows  that  there  is  an  objective  independent  of  man  to  be  aimed 
at,  but  rather  that  the  search  is  relative  to  the  searcher.  His  courageous 
working  out  of  this  position  is  extremely  valuable  as  pointing  a  fruitful 
direction  for  those  who  regard  knowing  as  a  good  in  itself,  but  who  have 
felt  disheartened  by  the  apparent  inability  of  knowing  to  achieve  a  syste- 
matic view  of  the  universe. 

Even  the  logical  factors  involved  in  knowing — and  for  these  Prof.  Baillie 
simply  refers  us  to  "current  logic" — differ  in  different  men.  Men  differ 
in  their  sense  of  what  is  clear  or  self-evident,  consistent  or  inconsistent ; 
in  the  reach,  complexity,  subtlety  and  precision,  of  their  intellects  ;  and 
thus  it  would  be  absurd  to  expect  any  measure  of  agreement  in  the  ulti- 
mate intellectual  attitude  of  different  men.  (The  difficulty  here  is  to  see 
how  to  understand  the  "logical  "  factors.  If  Prof.  Baillie's  view  is  correct, 
then  a  radically  different  view  of  the  logical  factors  from  that  of  the 
current  logic  seems  necessitated.)  The  way  of  intellect  is  simply  one  of 
the  ways  in  which  man  seeks  self-satisfaction  ;  and  it  is  to  be  considered 
as  parallel  in  its  nature  to  art  and  morality.  They  and  it  react  on  one 
another,  and  are  to  be  regarded  as  organically  related  parts  of  man's 
whole  nature,  which  seeks,  not  the  self-completeness  of  any  aspect,  but 
growth  through  complete  activity. 

This  general  attitude  (expressed  in  Essays  I.,  III.,  VI.,  VII.,  VIII.)  is 
confirmed  in  detail  by  the  accounts  of  perception,  judgment  and  infer- 
ence (in  the  second  essay),  of  memory  (in  Essay  IV.)  and  of  emotion 
(Essay  V.)  :  where  it  is  contended  that  each  aspect  of  the  self  makes  its 
own  unique  and  distinctive  contribution  to  knowledge,  which  cannot  be 
set  aside  in  the  interests  of  the  contribution  of  any  other  aspect,  and 
that  hence  the  ideal  of  systematic  completeness  cannot  be  supreme.  He 
speaks  occasionally  of  his  view  as  involving  an  appeal  to  intuition,  but 
intuition  means  more  than  the  simple  fact  that  each  aspect  of  the  self 
stands  on  its  own  feet  and  claims  ultimacy  within  its  own  sphere.  In- 
tuition is  bound  up  with  feeling.  He  speaks  (82)  of  the  emotional  thrill 
with  which  man  responds  to  selected  parts  of  his  environment  as  ' '  one  of 
the  most  mysterious  manifestations  of  mental  life,"  and  (61)  of  the  full 
joy,  the  complete  sense  of  fulfilment,  which  successful  thinking  brings  ; 
and  it  is  in  the  light  of  such  statements  that  we  should  read  the  brief 
account  of  intuition  on  page  74,  as  the  final  operation  of  the  mind  in  know- 
ing, "  inseparable  from  feeling  and  carrying  the  sense  of  completed  mental 
activity  or  free  self-fulfilment ".  It  is  this  state  of  mind  which  is  the  goal 
of  knowledge,  and  not  "a  system  of  thoughts  outside  the  mind". 

This  whole  view,  dealing  as  it  does  with  the  most  important  of  all  the 
philosophical  problems  of  to-day,  is  expounded  with  remarkable  lucidity 
and  vigour.  The  account  of  certain  non-logical  factors  in  knowledge  is 
the  most  careful  and  balanced  statement  we  have  yet  seen  on  this  subject. 
There  is  an  illuminating  final  essay  on  ' '  Laughter  and  Tears  "  which 
treats  the  subject  of  laughter  in  close  relation  with  its  opposite. 

A  companion  series  of  studies,  dealing  with  morality  and  citizenship, 


100  NEW  BOOKS. 

is  foreshadowed  in  the  preface.  Readers  of  the  present  volume  will  look 
forward  to  its  companion  with  great  interest. 

LEONARD  RUSSELL. 

The  Moral  and  Social  Significance  of  the  Conception  of  Personality.  By 
the  late  ARTHUR  GEORGE  HEATH,  M.A.,  sometime  Fellow  of  New 
College,  Oxford,  and  Lieutenant  in  the  6th  Batt.  Royal  West  Kent 
Regiment.  Oxford :  at  the  Clarendon  Press,  1921.  Pp.  viii,  159. 
Price  7s.  6d. 

All  who  have  read  the  Letters  of  Arthur  George  Heath,  and  the  brief  but 
fitting  memoir  by  Prof.  Gilbert  Murray  which  prefaced  them,  must  have 
realised,  even  if  they  did  not  know  him  in  life,  that  his  death  on  the  field 
of  battle  robbed  Oxford  and  New  College  of  a  singularly  fine  character 
and  a  mind  rich  in  promise  of  distinction.  They  will  turn  with  more  than 
ordinary  interest  to  this  short  essay,  which  gained  the  Green  Moral 
Philosophy  Prize  in  1914,  and  which  has  now  been  given  to  the  world  by 
his  friends  and  literary  executors,  notwithstanding  the  fact  that  Heath 
himself,  before  sailing  for  France,  advised  against  its  being  published  as 
it  stands.  The  decision  to  override  Heath's  own  judgment  must  have 
been  a  grave  and  difficult  one,  but  there  is  good  reason  to  feel  grateful  to 
the  editors  for  their  courage.  True,  the  essay,  as  they  recognise,  "will 
not  win  for  its  author  the  reputation  as  a  philosopher  which  he  would 
have  attained  if  he  had  lived  to  complete  his  life's  work"  (p.  iv),  but  it 
helps  one  to  understand  the  trend  of  philosophical  thought  among  the 
younger  generation  of  Oxford  teachers,  and  it  shows  Heath's  freshness 
and  independence  in  the  handling  of  a  well-worn  topic. 

Oxford,  it  is  clear,  is  turning  away  from  the  idealism  of  Green  and 
Caird,  Bosanquet  and  Bradley.  Even  Plato  is  mentioned  only  to  be 
criticised.  The  dominant  character  of  this  reaction  is,  broadly,  "  realistic  ". 
In  the  theory  of  knowledge,  its  leaders  insist  upon  the  distinction  between 
the  act  of  knowing  and  the  object  known.  In  political  theory,  they 
protest  against  the  "exaltation  of  the  State,"  against  the  "social  mysti- 
cism "  which  ascribes  to  the  State  a  consciousness  and  personality  higher 
than  those  of  its  individual  citizens,  and  expresses  itself  in  Hegel's  "  Es 
ist  der  Gang  Gofctes  in  der  Welt  dass  der  Staat  ist".  In  metaphysics, 
they  reject  the  absolute,  especially  when  conceived  as  an  infinite  person, 
and  construe  the  universe  pluralistically  as  a  society  of  finite  spirits.  All 
these  characteristics  of  a  realistic,  or  at  least  anti-idealistic,  movement  of 
thought  are  to  be  found  in  Heath's  essay,  though  from  its  pred  ominantly 
ethical  and  political  interest  the  emphasis  naturally  falls  on  the  second 
point,  viz.,  the  comparative  analysis  of  forms  of  social  organisation  as 
making  for  the  more  abundant  life  of  individual  minds.  \  "  We  are  persons 
in  order  that  we  may  become  personalities  "  (p.  4).  "  The  highest  goodness 
of  which  we  can  conceive  is  only  possible  ...  in  the  lives  of  finite 
persons  "  (p.  22).  "  In  the  world  of  spirit  the  differentiation  of  personality 
is  final  arid  sufficient "  (p.  39).  "  A  society  of  persons  knowing  the  truth, 
wishing  the  good,  loving  one  another  and  enjoying  the  fullness  of  their 
lives— such  is  the  ideal  of  any  unsophisticated  mind"  (p.  50).  Sentences 
like  these  recur  throughout  the  essay  :  they  strike  its  keynote.  The 
following  summary,  in  the  author's  own  words,  best  gives  the  total  effect : 
"  I  wish  to  establish  first  that  though  some  moral  goodness  may  be  found 
elsewhere  than  in  persons,  its  most  characteristic  forms  demand  person- 
ality :  that  equally  the  highest  goodness  of  which  we  can  conceive  would 
be  personal  goodness  :  that  it  would  further  be  the  goodness  of  finite 
personalities  who  could  in  no  way  be  absorbed  into  one  another  though 


NEW  BOOKS.  101 

they  could,  and  necessarily  would,  live  in  intercourse  with  each  other  :  but 
that  this  society  could  not  be  identified  with  the  State,  that  the  attempts 
to  elevate  the  State  into  a  moral  being  higher  than  any  finite  individual 
must  fail,  and  that  the  divergence  between  personal  development  and 
social  duty  is  in  some  sense  a  real  fact  ..."  (pp.  7,  8). 

The  argument  in  support  of  these  theses,  though  rather  uneven  in 
quality,  improves  steadily  as  the  essay  proceeds,  until  it  culminates  in  a 
really  fine  and  powerful  passage  in  which  Heath  prophesies  that  "as 
civilisation  advances  the  present  State  must  decline,  and  with  it  also  the 
economic  structure  which  the  State  at  present  partly  controls  and  partly 
reflects"  (p.  150).  This  decline  of  "law  and  politics "  is  to  come  about 
through  man's  advance  in  the  control  of  Nature  and  of  himself.  The 
whole  thought  reminds  one  of  Spinoza's  concept  of  jus  in  naturam,  to 
which,  however,  Heath  does  not  refer.  The  State,  to  him,  is  not  the 
""supreme  form  of  human  organisation  "  (p.  125),  for  he  restricts  the  term 
explicitly  to  the  sphere  of  power  of  the  "Sovereign  Legislature"  (ibid.). 
To  the  State,  so  conceived,  he  does  indeed  concede  the  very  important 
functions  of  being,  in  "the  common  interest,"  the  ultimate  court  of  con- 
trol over  all  other  forms  of  social  organisation  to  which  its  citizens  belong ; 
and  of  exercising  the  supreme  power  of  coercion  (Part  VII. ).  But  he 
insists  that  many  of  the  forms  of  social  organisation  which  the  State 
supervises  and  controls,  e.g.,  the  family,  or  the  church,  realise,  as  measured 
by  the  quality  of  individuals'  thoughts,  purposes  and  feelings,  higher 
moral  values  than  does  the  State.  Incidentally,  Heath  makes  some  sound 
remarks  on  the  relation  of  the  economic  to  other  motives  in  human  con- 
duct (Part  V.,  §  2),  and  shrewdly  points  out  that  the  socialisation  of 
industry  would  not  abolish  conflicts  of  interests,  but  only  alter  the 
machinery  for  settling  them,  by  substituting  the  methods  of  the  council 
chamber  for  the  methods  of  the  market  (Part  VI.,  §  3).  No  doubt,  he 
would  have  put  this  point  differently,  had  "  direct  action  "  been  within 
his  experience.  Throughout  he  is  much  concerned  to  argue  that  the  legal 
concept  of  the  personality  of  corporations  is  a  mere  fiction,  lest  it 
be  exploited  in  favour  of  a  metaphysical  personification  of  the  State. 
Everywhere  his  principle  is  that  "neither  in  the  State  nor  in  the  Church 
nor  any  lesser  grouping  can  you  find  a  unit-  of  value  higher  than  the 
individual  personality  "  (p.  89). 

In  the  section  on  Self-Realisation  (Part  HI.),  Heath  argues  with  much 
point  that  this  concept  is  too  vague  to  supply  a  standard  for  the  develop- 
ment of  a  man's  individuality.  So  far  as  it  is  positive,  it  calls  for  breadth 
rather  than  depth.  But  it  leaves  us  helpless  in  the  face  of  the  problem  of 
harmonising,  except  by  unsatisfactory  compromises,  such  conflicting  ele- 
ments of  the  ideal  as  action  and  contemplation,  personal  enjoyment  or 
self-cultivation  and  social  service.  Heath  does  not  appear  to  have  noticed 
that  his  point  here  is  fundamentally  the  same  as  that  which  Bradley 
makes  in  Appearance  and  Reality,  and  A.  E.  Taylor  in  The  Problem  of 
Conduct,  and  that  it  can  be  used  as  a  premise  for  conclusions  very  different 
from  his  own.  In  general,  morever,  his  preoccupation  with  the  ideal  of  a 
perfection  realised  discretely  in  as  many  individuals  as  possible  makes  him 
ignore  altogether  both  vicarious  suffering  and  vicarious  achievement.  Yet 
it  may  fairly  be  held  that  no  analysis,  be  it  of  individual  persons,  be  it  of 
social  life,  which  is  blind  to  these  two  things,  does  more  than  scratch  the 
surface. 

But  the  weakest  portions  of  the  essay,  to  my  mind  at  any  rate,  are 
Parts  I.  and  II.  The  foundation  of  Heath's  whole  position  is  given  in  this 
sentence  :  "it  appears  to  me  that  we  regard  nothing  as  good  in  itself  ex- 
cept states  of  consciousness  "  (p.  9).  This  judgment  is  nowhere  discussed. 
Ko  grounds  are  given,  no  elucidations  offered.  We  must  interpret  it,  I 


102  NEW  BOOKS. 

think,  as  implying  that  also  nothing  is  bad  in  itself  except  states  of  con- 
sciousness. Yet  there  is  nowhere  any  attempt  at  a  discussion  of  what  con- 
stitutes badness  and  goodness  in  states  of  consciousness.  If,  e.g.,  we 
insist  on  the  distinction  between  the  act  of  thinking  and  the  object  of 
thought  (p.  36),  the  question  at  once  arises  whether  goodness  and  badness 
belong  to  the  acts  by  themselves  (which  alone,  presumably,  can  be  described 
as  "  states  of  consciousness  "),  or  whether  they  depend  also  on  the  objects. 
Moreover,  in  spite  of  repeated  readings,  I  cannot  make  out  whether,  in 
Part  I.,  Heath  does  or  does  not  intend  to  distinguish  between  "  moral 
goodness  "and  other  forms  of  "  ultimate  value  ".  He  begins  by  distin- 
guishing them  and  enumerates  knowledge  of  the  truth,  creation  of  works 
of  art,  and  pleasure  as  non-moral  values.  But,  thereafter,  the  question  of 
the  "  goodness  "  or  "  value  "  of  states  of  consciousness  is  uniformly  treated 
as  if  it  were  exclusively  the  question  of  their  moral  goodness.  And  thin 
question  is  further  complicated  by  the  distinction  between  beings  who  are 
conscious  and  beings  who  are  self-conscious.  Only  the  latter,  aware  of  an 
alien  world  and  capable  of  memory  and  anticipation,  are  strictly  "  persons". 
Yet  persons  share  with  lower  animals  certain  emotions  and  impulses.  And 
thus  the  problem  is  posed  whether  these  emotions  and  impulses  "can 
have  a  place  in  [moral]  goodness  "  (p.  15)  when  they  occur  in  self-conscious 
persons  and,  again,  when  they  occur  in  unself-conscious  animals.  The 
whole  discussion  seems  lacking  in  clearness  and  grip.  Of  Part  II.,  which 
contains  Heath's  arguments  against  The  Idea  of  Infinite  Personality,  it  is 
enough  to  say  (1)  that,  so  far  as  they  are  polemical  (chiefly  against  Lotze 
and  Bosanquet)  they  bring  nothing  new  and  leave  one  wondering  whether 
Heath  really  understood  what  those  whom  he  criticises  seek  to  express ; 
and  (2),  that  so  far  as  he  insists  on  the  value  of  finite  beings,  and 
even  of  the  imperfections  and  limitations  of  finite  beings,  he  says 
nothing  which  an  absolutist  could  not  accept,  or  which  could  not  be 
paralleled,  e.g.,  from  Bosanquet's  writings.  With  the  question  whether 
a  finite  creature  is  merely  finite  he  does  not  deal.  He  simply  assumes  the 
affirmative. 

There  is  a  sentence  in  the  Conclusion  (p.  156)  which  makes  poignant 
reading.  "The  feeling  in  the  minds  of  many  sincere  and  loyal  citizens 
that  their  country  is  greater  than  themselves  has  to  be  set  aside  as  mis- 
leading, although  it  is  quite  true  that  the  individual  may  realise  the 
highest  within  his  powers  in  self-sacrificing  devotion  ".  Supposing  death 
were  an  experience  which  men  could  survive  and  learn  from,  what  should 
we  not  give  to  have  Heath's  own  comments  on  this  judgment  now  that  he 
has  himself  made  the  supreme  sacrifice  for  his  country  ? 

R.  F.  A.  H. 

Collected  Scientific  Papers.  By  JOHN  HENRY  POYNTING,  Sc.D.,  F.R.S., 
Mason  Professor  of  Physics  in  the  University  of  Birmingham.  Cam- 
bridge :  University  Press,  1920.  Pp.  xxxii  +  768. 

Friends  of  the  late  Prof.  Poynting — and  they  are  many — will  welcome 
this  handt-ome  memorial  volume  of  his  scientific  papers  which  has  recently 
been  published  by  the  Cambridge  Press.  It  has  been  edited  by  two  of 
his  junior  colleagues,  G.  A.  Shakespear  and  Guy  Barlow ;  and  interesting 
biographical  and  critical  notices  by  Sir  Oliver  Lodge,  Sir  Joseph  Larmor, 
Sir  J.  J.  Thomson  and  G.  A.  Shakespear,  have  been  inserted  as  an 
Introduction. 

J.  H.  Poynting  was  one  of  the  four  first  professors  of  the  Mason  College, 
Birmingham,  opened  in  1880  by  Huxley  (who  delivered  on  the  occasion 
his  notable  Address  on  "Science  and  Culture").  Poynting  had  been  a 
student  at  Owen's  College,  Manchester,  and  at  Trinity  College,  Cambridge, 


NEW  BOOKS.  103 

and  was  Third  Wrangler  in  the  Mathematical  Tripos  of  1876.  He  was 
elected  to  a  Fellowship  at  Trinity  in  1878,  and  then  began  in  the  Caven- 
dish Laboratory  under  Clerk  Maxwell  a  series  of  experiments  on  the 
mean  density  of  the  earth,  which  occupied  him  for  some  twelve  years. 
When  he  went  to  Birmingham  in  1880  he  had  the  opportunity  of  organis- 
ing a  laboratory  of  his  own,  and  in  it  one  valuable  piece  of  physical 
research  after  another  was  undertaken,  until  his  too  early  death  in  1914, 
at  the  age  of  sixty-two  years.  As  a  physicist  he  is  most  widely  known 
through  his  memoirs  "  On  the  Transfer  of  Energy  in  the  Electromagnetic 
Field"  (Phil.  Trans.,  A,  1884),  and  "On  Electric  Currents  and  the 
Electric  and  Magnetic  Induction  in  the  Surrounding  Field  "  (Phil.  Trans., 
A,  1888),  both  of  them  included  in  the  present  volume,  the  former 
culminating  in  what  Sir  Joseph  Larmor  describes  as  "  the  famous  result 
that  will  go  down  to  posterity  as  Poynting's  Theorem  ".  Not  only  did  he 
succeed  in  specifying  the  path  of  transfer  of  electric  energy  from  one 
material  system  to  another,  but  he  was  likewise  enabled  to  give  for  the 
first  time  as  a  very  special  case  the  dynamical  specification  of  a  ray  of 
light.  For  some  years  before  his  death  he  devoted  a  great  deal  of  atten- 
tion to  the  problems  of  radiation  and  radiation-pressure,  and  made  im- 
portant contributions  to  the  experimental  side  of  the  subject.  In  these 
researches  he  started  with  the  notion  of  a  beam  of  light  as  a  carrier  of 
momentum,  as  bearing  with  it  a  forward  push  ready  to  be  imparted  to 
any  surface  which  it  meets. 

Of  the  more  technical  papers  which  are  here  collected,  I  will  only  say 
that  many  of  them  give  even  to  an  outsider  like  myself  a  clearer  conception 
of  the  directions  in  which  physicists  have  recently  been  moving,  and  of  the 
tremendous  revolution  in  physical  theories  consequent  on  the  discovery 
of  radium,  than  can  readily  be  obtained  elsewhere.  But  Prof.  Poynting 
inherited  from  his  father  (the  author  of  a  book,  published  in  1860,  entitled 
Glimpses  of  the  Heaven  that  Lies  About  Us,  which  in  its  day  occasioned  a 
considerable  amount  of  discussion)  an  interest  in  metaphysical  inquiry  ; 
and  in  not  a  few  of  the  essays  contained  in  this  volume  he  is  to  be  found 
wrestling  with  the  philosophical  questions  that  lie  at  the  basis  of  physics, 
as  also  with  those  questions  of  philosophical  import  with  which  physics 
may  be  said  to  terminate. 

The  Address  to  Section  A  of  the  British  Association  in  1899  (pp. 
599-612)  is,  in  mf>re  ways  than  one,  anticipatory  of  Whitehead's  Address 
to  the  same  Section  in  1916.  Poynting  here  emphatically  maintains  that 
the  method  of  physical  science  consists  in  searching  for  likenesses  or 
similarities,  in  classing  together  resembling  events,  and  in  thus  furnishing 
a  concise  account  of  the  motions  and  changes  observed.  Physical  laws, 
he  urges,  are  just  brief  descriptions  of  observed  similarities.  And  he 
strongly  protests  (in  a  manner  that  reminds  one  of  Lotze)  against  phrase- 
ology encouraging  the  anthropomorphic  tendency  to  look  upon  physical 
laws  as  though  they  were  expressions  of  fixed  purpose  and  the  resulting 
constancy  of  action  as  though  they  were  commands  analogous  to  legal 
enactments.  E.<j. ,  gases  are  still  said  to  obey  or  to  disobey  Boyle's  Law, 
as  if  it  set  forth  an  ideal  or  perfect  gas  for  their  imitation  ;  and  radiators 
to  be  good  or  bad,  as  if  it  were  a  duty  on  their  part  to  radiate  well,  and 
as  if  there  were  failures  on  Nature's  part  to  come  up  to  the  proper 
standard. 

Nevertheless,  both  in  this  Address  and  in  other  papers,  Poynting  was 
constrained  to  admit  that  a  certain  amount  of  anthropomorphism  is  in 
science  inevitable.  The  ultimate  aim  of  physical  research  is,  he  thought, 
to  describe  sense-data  in  terms  of  sen^e-data.  But  for  science  at  its 
present  stage  to  be  confined  to  description  of  this  sort  would  mean  that 
great  and  innumerable  gaps  would  be  left  in  our  knowledge ;  and, 


104  NEW   BOOKS. 

consequently,  the  human  device  of  throwing  hypothetical  bridges  across 
these  gaps  to  connect  what  would  otherwise  be  detached  regions  is  bound 
to  prevail.  A  "true  physicist,"  a  physicist  who  was  a  physicist  alone, 
would,  no  doubt,  be  content  to  describe  merely  what  is  observed  in  the 
changes  of  energy,  to  say,  for  instance,  that  so  much  kinetic  energy  ceases 
and  that  so  much  light  appears,  or  that  so  much  light  comes  to  a  surface 
and  that  so  much  chemical  energy  takes  its  place.  The  human  mind,, 
however,  abhors  discontinuity  no  less  than  Nature  was  once  supposed  to 
abhor  a  vacuum,  and  accordingly  imagines  a  constitution  of  matter  and 
modifications  of  it  corresponding  to  the  different  kinds  of  energy,  such 
that  the  discontinuities  vanish,  and  one  form  of  energy  can  be  pictured  as 
passing  into  another,  while  yet  remaining  the  same  in  kind  throughout. 
Thus,  then,  deserting  the  field  of  perceived  fact,  the  physicist  constructs 
a  conception  of  natural  mechanism, — a  conception  which  enables  him  to 
explain  in  terms  of  motions  and  accelerations  all  the  various  occurrences 
of  Nature.  So  far,  the  only  foundation  which  has  served  him  for  this 
mechanical  explanation  has  been  the  atomic  and  molecular  hypothesis  of 
matter  ;  that  is  to  say,  he  connects  observed  conditions  and  changes  in 
gross  visible  matter  by  invisible  molecular  and  ethereal  machinery.  In 
other  words,  "while  the  building  of  Nature  is  growing  spontaneously 
from  within,  the  model  of  it,  which  we  seek  to  construct  in  our  descriptive 
science,  can  only  be  constructed  by  means  of  scaffolding  from  without,  a 
scaffolding  of  hypotheses  "  (p.  607).  Such  hypotheses  are  in  terms  of  our- 
selves rather  than  in  terms  of  Nature,  they  are  ejective  rjther  than 
objective  (e.g  ,  the  molecular  and  ethereal  machinery  has  been  designed, 
so  Prof.  Poynting  believed,  partly  because  our  most  highly  developed 
sense  is  that  of  sight) ;  but,  still,  the  circumstance  that  the  form  of  a 
hypothesis  may  change,  as  our  knowledge  extends,  lessens  in  no  way  its 
present  value  as  an  instrument  to  aid  us  in  the  search  for  truth.  We  can 
recognise  to  the  full  how  adequately  the  molecular  hypothesis,  for  example, 
enables  us  to  group  together  large  masses  of  fact  which,  without  it, 
would  be  scattered  apart,  and  continually  enables  investigators  to  formu- 
late new  questions  for  research. 

Several  of  the  papers  in  this  volume  deal  with  the  molecular  theory. 
No  more  succinct  or  lucid  account  of  its  history  has  been  written  than  the 
article  on  the  "  Atomic  Theory  (Mediaeval  and  Modern),"  which  is  here 
reprinted  (pp.  724-741)  from  Hastings'  Encyclopaedia,  an  article  which  is 
admirably  supplemented  by  the  two  shorter  papers,  entitled  "Mole- 
cules, Atoms  and  Corpuscles  "  (pp.  664-672)  and  "Mysteries  of  Matter  " 
(pp.  677-681).  While  consistently  maintaining  that  the  theory  is  only  a 
hypothesis,  which  it  is  at  least  conceivable  some  other  hypothesis  may 
displace,  Poynting  confessed  that  it  w;>s  to  him  most  difficult  to  suppose 
even  the  possibility  of  giving  up  the  idea  of  a  grained  structure  of  matter 
whatever  may  be  the  nature  of  the  grains.  In  discussing  the  latest 
theory  of  atomic  structure,  he  expresses  doubt  as  to  whether  the  mass 
of  electrons  can  be  sufficiently  accounted  for  by  the  magnetic  energy  of 
their  charges  when  in  motion.  Certainly,  he  argues,  all  our  measure- 
ments of  energy  involve  the  idea  of  mass,  and  he  makes  the  suggestion 
that  perhaps  the  magnetic  energy  in  the  space  round  the  moving  electron 
may  imply  the  existence  of  mass  in  that  space  to  serve  as  a  seat  for  the 
energy.  Were  this  so,  the  electric  theory  of  mass  would  only  take  the 
mass  from  the  inside  of  the  moving  sphere  and  spread  it  through  the 
outside  space,  so  that  we  should  come  back  again  to  the  Boscovich-Faraday 
conception  that  an  atom  is  wherever  its  force  acts — not  at  the  centre 
alone,  but  spread  out  through  all  space.  But,  from  the  point  of  view  of 
physics,  Poynting  did  not  see  his  way  to  reduce,  as  he  put  it,  all  to  force. 
"We  think  of  force  as  effort,  symbolised  by  muscular  effort;  and  if  we 


NEW  BOOKS.  105 

liave   force  alone,   it  is   difficult  to  assign  meaning  to  effort  acting  on 
effort "  (p.  730). 

In  the  light  of  these  considerations,  it  is  somewhat  surprising  to  find 
him,  contending  with  vehemence  that  in  purely  physical  inquiries  the  idea 
of  '  cause '  is  quite  out  of  place,  and  that  it  would  be  a  gain  to  clear 
thinking  if  we  could  abolish  the  word  from  scientific  description  (p.  602). 
For,  after  all,  the  idea  of  '  cause  '  is  surely  no  more  anthropomorphic  than 
is,  according  to  his'own  showing,  the  idea  of  force  ;  in  point  of  fact,  there 
is  little  doubt  that  the  primitive  representation  of  a  causal  connexion  is 
derived  like  the  idea  of  force  from  the  initiation  of  movement  by  muscular 
effort.  And  if  the  ultimate  aim  of  physical  science  is  to  describe  sense- 
data  in  terms  of  sense-data,  it  is  hard  to  see  why  'effort'  should  be 
deprived  of  its  significance,  for  it  is  as  distinctively  a  sense-datum  as  a 
colour  or  a  sound. 

The  essay  on  "Physical  Law  and  Life"  (pp.  686-698)  is  in  many 
respects  a  noteworthy  production.  'Prof.  Poynting  would  constitute  a 
sharp  antithesis  between  physical  and  mental  activity  and  could  not  see 
the  remotest  likelihood  of  our  ever  making  out  any  correspondence  between 
the  two.  In  a  physical  system,  quantitative  values  can  be  assigned  to  the 
different  conditions,  and  the  resulting  motion  can  be  foretold  from  their 
combination.  But  we  have,  he  insisted,  no  such  method  of  rneasuriEg 
motives  in  the  mental  life.  We  have  absolutely  no  means  of  determining 
which  motive  is  the  '  stronger,'  and  can  only  assign  such  strength  to  that 
irhich  ultimately  prevails.  There  is,  therefore,  no  kind  of  analogy  in 
fetich  a  procedure  to  physical  measurement.  "  Every  time  an  intention  is 
formed  in  the  mind  and  a  deliberate  choice  is  made  we  have  an  event 
unlike  any  previous  event.  Freedom  of  will  is  a  simple  fact,  unlike 
anything  else,  inexplicable  "  (p.  687). 

I  must  not  dwell  on  the  acute  criticism  of  Herbert  Spencer's  views  on 
the  foundations  of  our  belief  in  the  indestructibility  of  matter  and  the 
conservation  of  energy  (pp.  588-598),  nor  on  the  valuable  Address  on 
"The  Growth  of  the  Modern  Doctrine  of  Energy"  (pp.  565-575).  But, 
in  view  of  the  current  discussions  on  relativity,  attention  ought  to  be 
called  to  the  delightful  little  piece  on  "  Overtaking  the  Rays  of  Light  " 
(pp.  552-556),  originally  published  in  1883.  Supposing  an  observer 
moving  from  the  earth  with  twice  the  velocity  of  light  towards  Sirius, 
Prof.  Poynting  pictures  that  observer  seeing  the  events  of  the  last  ten 
years,,  all  in  the  reverse  order.  The  earth  will  appear  to  him  to  go  the 
wrong  way  round  the  sun  and  to  rotate  the  wrong  way  on  its  axis  ;  rivers 
will  appear  to  him  steadily  to  flow  up  towards  their  source,  showers  of 
rain  to  start  from  the  earth  and  rise  towards  the  clouds  ;  old  men  will 
seem  to  be  dying  into  life,  walking  backwards  all  their  days,  growing 
younger  and  younger,  until  at  last  they  are  born  out  of  the  world  as 
flourishing  babies,  at  the  mature  age  of  three  score  years  and  ten.  Query, 
will  the  relat  vist  maintain  that  presuming  this  observer  had  a  fair 
knowledge  of  physics  and  physiology  he  would  yet  have  no  means  of 
•ascertaining  whether  he  were  moving  towards  the  rays  of  light  or  they 
were  moving  towards  him  ? 

The  volume  contains  a  fine  portrait  of  the  author  and  a  complete  list  of 
hie  published  works. 

G.  DAWES  HIOKS. 

Psychology  and  Mystical  Experience.  By  JOHN  HOWLEY,  M.A.,  Professor 
of  Philosophy,  Galway.  London:  Keyan,  Paul,  Trench,  Trubner  & 
Co.,  Ltd.  St.  Louis  M.O. :  B.  Herder  Book  Company.  1920.  Pp.  275. 

There  is  more  in  religious  experience,  according  to  the  writer  of  this  book, 
than  mere  psychology  is  competent  to  explain  ;  but  there  is  also  a  residuum 


106  NEW  BOOKS. 

with  which  it  may  profitably  take  to  do ;  and  he,  as  an  orthodox  Catholic; 
and  a  psychologist,  addresses  himself  to  that.  His  work  falls  into  two  Parts 
and  an  Introduction.  The  Introduction,  which  is  the  nucleus  out  of  which, 
as  he  tells  us,  the  whole  grew,  offers  a  general  view  of  religious  experience. 
Part  I.  then  treats  of  Conversion,  while  Part  II.,  going  a  stage  deeper,. 
makes  a  study  especially  of  mystic  experience  and  is  entitled  Introversion. 

One  may  gather  what  has  been  the  generating  interest  behind  the  workr 
readily  enough,  from  the  Introduction  itself.  The  Author  appears  to  have 
gone  out  to  see  whether  a  mystic  experience  whereof  Catholicism  might  be 
regarded  as  the  peculiar  custodian  could  be  distinguished  effectively  from 
the  many  other  things  which  seem  like  it  but  perhaps  are  not  the  same. 
And  throughout  its  whole  course,  his  thought  keeps  up  what  might  be  des- 
cribed as  a  very  able,  or  at  anyrate  a  very  creditable,  running  fight  with 
divers  irregularities  in  the  way  of  religious  experience  both  within  the 
Church's  pale  and  without.  It  would  even  appear  at'points  that  it  is  the 
Author's  opinion  that  while  the  "agnostic  psychologist,"  with  his  merely 
scientific  equipment,  may  make  something  of  the  mysticism  of  a  Molinos  e>r 
a  Madame  Guyon,  of  Quakerism  or  Christian  Science,  of  Buddhism, 
Theosophy  or  what  not,  he  is  baffled  when  confronted  by  the  true  mystic 
experience  of  Catholicism. 

But  the  Author's  acute  and  learned  defence  of  his  views  of  what 
constitutes  true  mystic  experience,  may  probably  be  found  of  much  more 
permanent  interest  than  his  effort  to  credit  this  true  mysticism  especially  to 
the  Catholic  Church.  It  is  an  important  issue  intrinsically,  which  in  his 
hands  takes  the  characteristically  ecclesiastical  shape  of  a  question  as  regards 
the  respective  merits  of  two  ways  of  devotion,  namely  Quietism  and  the 
Prayer  of  Quiet.  Presuming  that  the  former  is  the  mother  of  all  disorder, 
while  the  latter  has  the  beginnings  of  true  mystic  expeiience  in  it,  he  asks 
what  really  is  the  difference  of  the  two.  And  the  answer  arrived  at  in  the 
introductory  chapter  covers  very  much  of  what  the  Author  eventually  has 
to  say  about  true  mysticism  and  false.  He  finds  that  in  the  Prayer  of  Quiet 
the  mind  is  in  contact  with  something  genuinely  "  given,"  while  in  Quietism 
it  has  only  worked  itself  up  into  a  certain  state.  And  the  criterion  by 
which  he  makes  the  distinction  is  the  presence  in  the  one  experience  and 
the  absence  from  the  other  of  a  certain  degree  of  attention.  The  pre- 
supposition seems  to  be  that  if  the  soul  is  dealing  with  a  "  given,"  then  that- 
with  which  it  is  occupied  will  not  be  merely  given  to  it  but  will  elicit  its  at- 
tention and  activity  to  some  degree.  There  will  be  some,  however  faint, 
sense  of  concentrating  on  it.  There  will  be  attention,  even  if  "passive" 
attention.  Where  attention  is  wholly  absent  [as  we  should  say,  where  the 
given  is  merely  given]  the  experience  is  a  spurious  one.  This,  the  Author 
surmises,  is  the  case  with  the  Quietists.  Quietism  "  would  seem  to  have 
passivity  without  attention,  to  be  a  rest  in  self  rather  than  a  rest  in  God  " 
p.  23). 

The  formula  just  quoted  contains  in  nuce  the  author's  substantial  criti- 
cism of  all  the  ways  of  mystic  experience  which  he  regards  as  mistaken, 
from  the  Protestant  variety  of  "conversion-phenomena"  to  the  religion* 
of  the  East.  There  is  an  inertia  in  them.  Thus  he  quotes  by  way  of 
warning,  certain  comfortings  from  Falconi  (Letter  to  a  Spiritual  Daughter) 
in  the  matter  of  the  criteria  of  a  true  spirit  of  devotion. 

"  Be  careful  when  doing  what  I  advised  you,  not  to  occupy  yourself  with, 
considering  that  God  is  present  in  your  soul  and  in  your  heart.  For  al- 
though that  is  a  good  thing  ...  it  would  not  be  to  believe  it  with  sufficient 
simplicity.  .  .  .  Neither  worry  yourself  to  know  whether  your  prayer  goes 
well  or  badly.  Don't  trifle  with  yourself  ...  in  thinking  whether  or  no 
you  practise  the  virtues  I  have  marked  for  you  or  other  such  matters. 
This  would  be  to  occupy  your  mind  with  these  feeble  considerations  and 
break  the  thread  of  perfect  prayer." 


NEW  BOOKS.  107 

So  also  Molinos, 

"Annihilation  to  be  perfect,  should  extend  to  the  judgments,  actions, 
inclinations,  desires,  thoughts,  to  all  the  substance  of  life." 

And  Malaval, 

"We  must  think  of  nothing  and  desire  nothing  for  as  long  a  time  as 
possible." 

And  again  Guy  on, 

"  This  divine  life  becomes  natural  to  the  soul.  As  the  soul  no  longer  feels, 
sees  or  knows  itself,  it  sees  nothing  of  God,  understands  nothing,  distin- 
guishes nothing.  There  is  no  longer  love,  light,  or  knowledge." 

"Thus,"  proceeds  the  Author,  commenting  on  these  errors,  "a  type  of  con- 
templation which  had  so  largely  contributed  to  the  sanctification  t  f  the 
companions  of  St.  Chantal  was  perverted  into  a  system  of  psychic  inertia." 
And  having  found  in  mental  inertia  the  root  of  the  evil  he  proceeds  to  find 
here  also  a  characteristic  feature  of  current  non-Catholic  systems  generally. 
"We  have  not  only  our  Quietists  to-day,"  he  says,  "but  we  have  this  in- 
duced passivity,  this  psychic  kenosis,  as  part  and  parcel  of  processes 
employed  by  spiritists,  faith  healers,  Christian  Scientists,  New  Thought 
folk,  indeed  of  all  seekers  after  the  psychic  Beyond  who  are  unwilling  to  be 
simple,  humble,  and  obedient.  They  look  to  find  the  Beyond  and  they  find 
themselves,  to  their  own  destruction." 

A  touch  of  the  nastiness  of  the  official  ecclesiastic  is,  we  are  afraid, 
inseparable  from  the  tone  of  this  whole  book.  But  it  would  be  a  pity  to 
let  this  or  any  other  adventitious  feature  conceal  from  us  the  importance 
of  the  task  of  distinguishing  true  and  false  in  just  the  region  where  the 
author  is  trying  to  distinguish  them.  It  is  fairly  plain  that  there  is  a  good 
mysticism  and  a  bad,  however  unlikely  it  is  that  any  one  body  of  people 
should  have  a  monopoly  of  the  former.  But  has  our  Author  got  hold  of 
the  distinction  ?  It  is  possible  that  he  has.  If  so,  it  is  highly  unlikely  to 
prove  in  the  end  to  be  a  line  of  distinction  between  sect  and  sect  of 
mystics,  as  he  thinks,  but  simply  one  between  the  mysticism  which  is  truly 
religious  and  that  which  is  not,  a  line  of  distinction  falling  within  all  the 
sects.  If  this  point  can  be  made,  then  much  interest  attaches  to  the 
author's  religious  standpoint.  All  recipes  for  the  treatment  of  the  soul, 
whether  derived  via  St.  Ignatious  or  via  Freud,  would  appear  to  be  double- 
edged  weapons,  capable  of  the  basest  uses  as  well  as  the  best ;  and  the  only 
guarantee  against  their  detrimental  use  would  seem  to  lie  in  the  circum- 
stance that  these  powers  are  recognised  as  being  derived  from  something 
which  is,  in  some  sense,  as  our  Author  insists,  beyond  psychology.  We 
should  at  least  have  the  assent  of  this  Author  to  the  view  that  all  psycho- 
logical medicine  must  in  the  last  resort  be  religious  ;  that  that  which 
places  such  instruments  as  its  in  the  discoverer's  hands,  must  itself  power- 
fully control  the  discoverer's  will,  if  the  discovery  is  not  ultimately  to  do 
harm. 

J.  W.  SCOTT. 

The  Psychology  of  Functional  Neuroses.  By  H.  L.  HOLLINGWORTH, 
Associate  Professor  of  Psychology  in  Columbia  University.  New 
York :  D.  Appleton  &  Co.,  1920.  Pp.  xiv  +  260.  No  price  given. 

This  book  is  based  on  experience  gained  by  the  author  at  U.S.A.  General 
Hospital  No.  30  during  the  latter  part  of  the  war.  This  hospital  was 
devoted  exclusively  to  persistent  psychoneurotic  cases,  of  which  about 
1200  consecutive  examples  were  closely  studied.  Prof.  Hollingworth  is 
not  a  medical  man  and  was  not  concerned  with  the  treatment  of  patients. 
His  function  as  Director  of  the  Hospital  Psychological  Service  seems  to 


108  NEW  BOOKS. 

have  been  to  organise  a  systematic  study  of  patients  by  means  of  intelli- 
gence tests  and  analogous  methods.  The  large  number  of  cases  available 
for  observation  has  enabled  him  to  collect  a  mass  of  statistical  material 
which  cannot  fail  to  be  of  interest  and  value  to  students  of  the  subject. 
Moreover,  as  he  justly  observes,  the  declaration  of  the  armistice  about 
midway  in  the  course  of  the  investigation  "constituted,  on  a  wholesale 
scale  entirely  unanticipated,  a  magnificent  experiment  in  psychotherapy. 
The  therapeutic  effects  of  this  event  were  not  only  observe  1  in  the  casual 
way  so  frequently  reported,  but  quantitative  measure  was  secured  of  the 
differential  effects  in  the  case  of  the  various  diagnostic  groups." 

It  is  not  possible  even  to  summarise  here  the  statistical  results  obtained, 
which  occupy  some  thirty  tables  in  the  book,  but  it  is  probable  that  few 
more  comprehensive  surveys  of  the  intelligence  and  mental  age  of  different 
types  of  psychoneurotic  have  been  made,  if,  indeed,  the  present  data  have 
•any  parallel  at  all.  Of  considerable  interest  also  is  the  chapter  devoted 
to  "  Irregularity  of  Profile  "  in  which  it  is  made  clear  that  psychoneurotics 
give  test  performances  which  are  clearly  distinguishable  from  those  of 
mentally  deficient  persons,  even  although  the  mean  score  for  a  number  of 
tests  is  the  same  in  each  class.  Whereas  the  mentally  deficient  show  low 
performances  all  round,  the  psychoneurotics  produce  the  same  mean  result 
by  scoring  abnormally  low  in  some  tests  and  quite  high  in  others.  They 
show,  in  fact,  a  high  degree  of  '  scattering '  and  the  average  deviation  of 
their  scores  from  the  median  is  much  greater  than  for  mental  defectives. 
In  this  way  it  is  possible  to  arrange  types  of  disorder  in  a  series  of  which 
each  number  approximates  more  closely  to  all-round  mental  deficiency 
type.  The  order  given  by  Prof.  Hollingworth  is :  Hysteria,  Epilepsy, 
Concussion,  Neurasthenia,  Psychoneurosis,  Constitutional  Psychopathy, 
Mental  Deficiency.  Provided  that  we  can  be  quite  sure  just  what  we 
mean  by  these  diagnostic  terms  it  seems  as  if  this  method  of  research 
might  well  prove  fruitful. 

Enough  has  been  said  to  show  that  the  book  contains  plenty  of  facts 
for  the  student  of  functional  disorders,  and  it  is  necessary  to  pay  some 
attention  to  the  earlier  and  more  theoretical  chapters.  These,  it  must 
be  confessed,  are  less  satisfactory  than  those  just  dealt  with.  Prof. 
Hollingworth  rightly  deplores  the  tendency  observable  in  some  quarters 
to  take  refuge  in  technical  jargon  instead  of  att3mpting  to  give  true 
explanations  of  phenomena.  He  deprecates,  not  wholly  unjustly  perhaps, 
the  use  of  such  words  or  phrases  as  i  symbolism,'  '  regression,'  '  transfer  of 
libido,'  '  siphoning  of  affects,'  etc.,  and  proposes  to  substitute  the  concept 
of  'redintegration' — a  term  borrowed  from  Hamilton  and  slightly 
modified  to  suit  modern  psychological  thought.  By  this  term  is  meant 
the  tendency  of  a  single  repeated  element  of  a  former  complex  situation 
to  evoke  in  a  psychoneurotic  the  whole  complex  reaction  which  originally 
corresponded  to  that  situation ;  as,  for  instance,  when  tha  banging  of  a 
door  causes  a  patient  to  react  in  every  respect  as  he  did  in  a  battle- 
situation  of  which  shell  and  gun  explosions  were  one  feature.  This 
mechanism  is,  he  thinks,  adequate  to  bear  the  whole  weight  of  ex- 
planation in  the  realm  of  the  psychoneuroses,  but  this  optimistic  view 
will  scarcely  be  shared  by  psychologists  in  general.  To  say  that  a  single 
element  tends  to  recall  the  whole  of  which  it  once  formed  a  part  and  to 
evoke  the  corresponding  complex  reaction  is  a  truism  which  amounts  to 
no  more  than  a  re-statement  of  the  Law  of  Association  ;  it  does  not  in 
any  way  explain  why,  in  substantially  identical  situations,  one  man  should 
become  paralysed,  another  mute,  a  third  deaf,  and  a  fourth  blind,  although 
it  makes  it  easy  to  understand  why,  when  partially  recovered,  each  should 
relapse  into  his  own  form  of  derangement  for  the  same  apparently 
inadequate  cause.  Apart  from  these  and  similar  criticisms  which  seem 


NEW  BOOKS.  109 

fatal  to  the  conception  as  an  explanatory  hypothesis,  there  is  nothing  to 
be  said  against  the  way  in  which  the  idea  is  worked  out,  and  the  chapter  on 
the  Levels  of  Redintegration  Response  is  not  uninteresting  from  the 
point  of  view  of  general  psychology. 

It  is  however  for  the  facts  rather  than  for  the  theories  to  be  found  in  it 
that  the  book  will  be  helpful. 

W.  WHATELY  SMITH. 

Military  Psychiatry  in  Peace  aad  War.  By  C.  STANFORD  READ,  M.D* 
(Lond.).  With  two  charts.  London  :  Lewis  &  Co.,  1920.  Pp.  vi, 
168. 

Of  the  many  psychological  books  resulting  from  the  War,  this  is  one  of 
the  best;  for  the  writer  is  fully  equipped  in  normal  and  morbid  psy- 
chology ;  he  has  had  charge  of  neurological  wards  and  has  visited  all  the 
war  mental  hospitals  in  France  and  Great  Britain.  The  book  is  at  once  a 
contribution  to  the  positive  study  of  insanity  and  an  important  com- 
mentary on  the  "psychogenic origin "  of  the  psychoses.  "Those  who  take 
up  an  essentially  materialistic  standpoint  see  the  essential  factors  in  the 
toxins  produced  by  disease  and  exhaustion,  in  the  inhalations  of  noxious 
gases,  in  the  effects  of  direct  or  indirect  concussion  brought  about  by 
high  explosives.  Others  believe  that  the  main  bulk  of  the  psychoses  are 
psychogenic  in  origin  and  look  to  mental  conflict  as  the  great  factor  to 
study.  I  hold  this  latter  view-point  and  shall  endeavour  to  show  that 
this  is  as  true  in  the  psychoses  of  war  as  it  is  of  peace  "  (p.  25).  Dr.  Read 
first  analyses  the  psychology  of  the  soldier.  The  chapter  is  an  illuminat- 
ing practical  application  of  Freudian  views.  He  comments  on  the  con- 
fusions due  to  the  failure  of  the  academic  alienists  of  the  past  to 
distinguish  between  the  insanities  proper  and  the  psycho-neuroses. 
"  Before  the  Commission  which  sat  to  enquire  into  the  recruiting  problem, 
in  the  evidence  given  by  the  military  authorities,  the  opinion  was  freely 
expressed  that  if  a  man  was  fit  enough  to  do  any  form  of  work  in  civil 
life,  he  was  fit  to  do  that  work  in  the  army.  Never  was  there  a  greater 
fallacy.  Large  numbers  of  cases  which  have  been  returned  from  overseas 
with  psychopathic  symptoms  freely  illustrate  the  falsity  of  this  statement. 
The  mental  factor  has  not  had  anything  like  the  consideration  it  should 
have  received  "  (p.  24).  These  ideas  are  applied  in  detail  to  leading  forms 
of  insanity,  for  example,  dementia  praecox,  paranoid  states,  confusional 
states,  manic  depressive  states,  mental  deficiency,  alcoholic  psychoses, 
epilepsy  and  epileptic  psychoses,  psycho-neurotic  disorders,  malingering, 
suicide— all  as  affected  by  war  conditions.  The  book  is  well  documented 
from  other  researches.  From  every  point  of  view,  it  deserves  to  be  placed 
among  the  best  handbooks  of  psychiatry. 

W.  L.  M. 

Psychologie  de  I' Enfant  ei  Pedagogic  Expe'rimentale.  By  Dr.  ED- 
CLAPAREDE,  Professor  of  Geneva  University.  Eighth  edition,  with 
a  complementary  preface.  Geneva  :  Kundig,  1920.  Pp.  1  +  570. 

This  new  edition  of  Claparede's  well-known  work  on  educational  psychology 
contains  an  introduction  of  considerable  length  in  which  the  author  en- 
deavours to  define  clearly  his  attitude  towards  his  subject.  He  urges  that 
education  must  be  established  upon  a  scientific  basis  which  takes  "know- 
ledge of  the  child "  for  a  starting-point.  Hitherto  emphasis  has  been 
laid  upon  the  subject  taught  rather  than  upon  the  child  to  whom  it  is 
taught.  Thus  we  discuss  whether  education  should  be  classical,  scientific 
or  vocational,  and  ignore  the  most  important  consideration  of  all,  t.e  ,  that 


110  NEW  BOOKS. 

no  scheme  of  education  can  succeed  which  is  not  adapted  to  the  mental  and 
moral  life  of  the  child. 

Claparede  deals  in  detail  with  current  objections  against   "scientific 


1.  The    "common  sense"    objection  that   the   power  of  judging  and 
weighing  educational    values  possessed    by  the    ordinary  individual  is 
adequate  will  not  hold  good,  for  on  every  educational  problem  that  has 
been  proposed  "  common  sense  "  gives  conflicting  verdicts. 

2.  It  is  true  that  the  best  educators  are  born  rather  than  made  ;  but  at 
the  same  time  the  teacher  needs  exact  knowledge  of  his  craft,  just  as  the 
"  born  musician  "  needs  a  knowledge  of  technique  in  music. 

3.  Some  say  that  "experience  is  the  best  and  only  school".     What  is 
really  required  is  a  knowledge  of  the  way  to  profit  by  experience,  and  that 
knowledge  demands  of  the  teacher  a  study  of  the  human  material  with 
which  he  has  to  deal . 

Claparede  points  out  that  the  demand  for  the  application  of  experimental 
psychology  to  education  has  come  mainly  from  the  teachers  themselves,  who 
are  of  all  people  the  best  acquainted  with  the  defects  of  the  present  state 
of  affairs. 

The  book  as  a  whole  is  by  now  too  well  known  to  need  detailed  descrip- 
tion. It  contains  a  vast  mass  of  material,  some  of  which  is  perhaps  rather 
uncritically  reported,  but  most  of  which  is  interesting.  The  presentation 
is  clear,  and  what  general  discussion  is  entered  upon  is  for  the  most  part 
extremely  well-conducted.  It  may  safely  be  said  that  there  is  hardly 
another  book  which  contains  so  much  information  of  use  to  the  psycho- 
logically-minded teacher  ;  and  the  information  given  is  always  expressed  in 
a  most  attractive  and  suggestive  manner. 

F.  C.  B. 

Personlichlteit  und  Weltanschauung :  psychologische  Untersuchungen  zu 
Religion,  Kunst  und  Philosophie.  By  RICHARD  MULLER-FBEIENFELS. 
Leipzig  and  Berlin  :  B.  G.  Teubner,  1919.  Pp.  xii,  274. 

This  work,  which  the  Preface  assures  us  was  substantially  complete  when 
the  War  broke  out,  is  a  singularly  well  documented  and  persuasive  plea  for 
what  the  author  calls  '  psychological  relativism,'  meaning  thereby  what  is 
otherwise  known  as  personalism  or  humanism.  It  aims  at  showing  * '  to 
an  extent  not  hitherto  attempted,  that  a  man's  Weltanschauung  is  the 
necessary  result  of  the  psychological  endowment  his  life  reveals  "  (p.  264). 
It  attains  its  aim  by  distinguishing  a  number  of  psychological  types  and 
tendencies,  such  as  men  of  feeling,  action  and  thought,  depressed  and 
exalted,  dynamic  and  static,  aggressive  and  pacific,  visualising,  audile  and 
motor,  concrete  and  abstract,  pluralistic  and  monistic,  types,  tracing  their 
manifestations  historically  in  the  actual  lives  and  works  of  artists,  philoso- 
phers and  religious  leaders,  and  concluding  with  a  more  detailed  study  of  the 
personality  of  Luther,  Goethe,  Wagner,  Diirer,  and  Kant,  and  its  influence 
upon  their  work.  The  book  is  well  written,  and  makes  out  its  case.  It 
should  prove  a  valuable  corrective  of  the  one-sided,  fanatical  and  ex- 
aggerated *  absolutism  '  that  was  rampant  in  the  German  philosophic  world 
before  the  War,  all  the  more  on  account  of  its  conciliatory,  and  even 
apologetic,  tone.  At  the  same  time  the  author  contends  that  his 
relativism  is  not  scepticism  ;  it  merely  recognises  the  facts  that  truths 
for  man  are  not  absolute,  that  no  single  doctrine  is  valid  for  literally  all 
and  that  the  various  ultimate  attitudes  towards  the  world  are  irrefutable, 
and  appeal  variously  to  different  characters,  and  it  leaves  open  the  possibility 
that  the  total  truth  may  eventually  be  composed  by  collecting  together 
the  personal  views  of  all  (p.  273).  He  might  well  have  added  two  more 


NEW  BOOKS.  Ill 

points ;  one  that  absolute  agreement,  if  it  were  possible,  would  yield  a 
-world  dull  and  intolerable,  like  a  chorus  in  which  every  member  sang 
precisely  the  same  note,  the  other  that  the  greater  the  variety  of  views 
tolerated,  the  greater  and  more  certain  would  be  the  selection  of  those 
that  had  superior  value,  either  intrinsically  or  relatively  to  the  personalities 
to  which  they  appealed. 

F.  C.  S.  SCHILLER. 

Fugitive  Essays.     By  JOSIAH  ROYCE,   with  an  introduction  by  Dr.   J. 
LOEWENBERG.     Harvard  University  Press,  1920.     Pp.  429. 

Most  of  these  essays — all,  in  fact,  except  the  last  three  of  them — were 
written  between  1879  and  1882.  As  the  reader  of  James's  Letters  will 
remember,  Royce,  at  this  period,  was  a  young  man  of  less  than  thirty, 
-eagerly  sharpening  his  philosophical  spurs,  but  feeling  himself  cabined 
within  the  immensities  of  the  Pacific  coast,  and  complaining,  indeed,  that 
fie  was  '  the  solitary  philosopher  between  Behrings'  Strait  and  Tierra  del 
Fuego  '.  '  The  World  Spirit,'  however,  to  quote  him  once  more,  '  found 
him  at  his  tasks  in  a  certain  place  that  looks  down  upon  the  Bay  of  San 
Francisco,'  and  was  so  far  propitious  to  him  as  to  see  to  the  publication 
of  most  of  these  essays.  Indeed,  it  found  a  home  for  some  half  a  dozen 
of  them  locally  in  The  Californian  and  in  The  Berkeley  Quarterly. 

Neither  the  editor  of  these  essays  (Dr.  Loewenberg,  of  Berkeley,  whose 
piety  as  a  Californian  blends  with  his  admiration  for  Royce's  life  work 
and  reaches  a  point  not  far  short  of  idolatry)  nor  anyone  else  would  claim 
that  these  Fugitive  Essays  attain  the  level  of  Royce's  mature  work.  What 
is  claimed  for  them  is  that  they  are  valuable  in  themselves,  since  Royce 
*  simply  could  not  be  trivial, '  and  that  they  show  a  very  interesting  and 
signal  continuity  in  the  progress  of  Royce's  philosophy.  The  editor  at- 
tempts to  demonstrate  this  continuity  in  a  valuable  but  slightly  ponderous 
introduction  of  some  forty  pages,  and  he  certainly  succeeds  in  giving 
chapter  and  verse  for  his  opinions,  although  he  seems,  to  the  present 
writer,  to  read  somewhat  more  into  his  extracts  than  they  can  legitimately 
bear. 

Opinions,  no  doubt,  will  differ  concerning  the  value  of  the  essays 
themselves,  and  some  may  even  think  that  it  is  always  a  sound  rule  to 
leave  the  ephemeral  and  comparatively  immature  work  of  distinguished 
men  in  the  obscurity  which  the  authors  have  not  seen  fit  to  disturb.  On 
the  other  hand,  Royce  was  so  clearly  one  of  the  great  leaders  in  the 
thought  of  a  continent,  and  so  responsive  to  the  ideas  of  his  time,  that 
the  history  of  his  philosophical  development  has  a  great  deal  of  signifi- 
cance for  the  whole  story  of  American  philosophy  in  the  generation  before 
the  war,  and  these  essays  are  very  welcome  on  this  account.  Royce  him- 
self wished  for  no  formal  biography,  apparently  because  he  thought  that 
biographies  of  the  usual  kind  are  only  impertinent  chronicles  of  irrelevant 
accidents.  What  counted,  he  thought,  was  a  man's  work  and  a  man's 
mind.  But  he  had  a  high  respect  for  history,  and  he  would  have  been 
the  last  to  belittle  any  attempt  to  illustrate  the  way  in  which  the  World 
Spirit  seizes  hold  of  those  it  has  chosen. 

JOHN  LAIRD. 

The  Moral  and  Political  Philosophy  of  John  Locke.  By  STIRLING  POWER 
LAMPRECHT,  Ph.D.  New  York :  Columbia  University  Press,  1918. 
Pp.  viii,  168. 

This  work  comprises  three  books,  which  treat  respectively  of  (1)  The  tra- 
dition in  moral  and  political  philosophy  before  the  time  of  Locke  ;  (2) 


112  NEW  BOOKS. 

The  moral  philosophy  of  Locke  ;  (o)  The  social  and  political  philosophy 
of  Locke.  In  the  introductory  book  Hobbes  and  Filmer  are  dealt  with  at 
some  length,  the  remaining  chapters  being  devoted  to  a  more  general  ex- 
position of  the  current  conception  of  the  '  law  of  nature '  and  of  the  views 
of  the  seventeenth  century  Deists  in  their  bearing  on  ethics.  This  cannot 
be  regarded  as  a  complete  account  of  the  historical  setting  of  this  aspect 
of  Locke's  Thought,  and  it  is  to  be  regretted  that  Dr.  Lamprecht  did  not 
see  his  way  to  deal  more  fully  with  the  theories  of  Cumberland  and  the 
Cambridge  Platonists  in  this  country  and  with  Grotius  and  Puffendorf 
among  continental  thinkers,  to  none  of  whom  is  there  more  than  an  oc- 
casional reference. 

The  exposition  here  given  of  Locke's  moral  philosophy  is  the  most 
elaborate  attempt  which  has  yet  been  made  to  elucidate  his  thought  on 
this  subject.  The  writer  has  made  a  careful  study  of  his  text  and  has 
done  well  to  supplement  the  scanty  indications  of  the  Essay  by  reference 
to  Locke's  minor  writings,  including  his  answers  to  some  of  his  early 
critics.  But  while  he  thus  presents  us  with  all  the  relevant  materials,  he 
does  not  seem  to  me  to  be  equally  successful  in  his  interpretation  of  them. 
Locke's  ethical  theory  on  the  face  of  it  contains  elements  which  are  not 
usually  found  in  combination  and  are  not  easily  reconciled.  Under  such 
circumstances  the  first  business  of  the  historian  is  to  endeavour  to  ascer- 
tain how  the  different  elements  were  related  to  each  other  in  his  own 
thought.  Only  when  this  has  been  done  can  the  degree  of  coherence  at- 
tained be  profitably  discussed.  We  may  not  be  able  at  the  end,  in 
Dr.  Lamprecht's  words,  "to  fit  all  he  said  into  one  harmonious  whole," 
but  we  are  not  driven  to  the  alternative  of  supposing  that  he  committed 
himself  to  a  number  of  different  and  inconsistent  positions,  which  he 
never  thought  of  relating  to  each  other.  On  the  contrary,  it  seems  clear 
that  the  different  elements  of  his  theory  were  regarded  by  him  as  comple- 
mentary to  each  other.  Thus,  while  maintaining  that  the  essential  part 
of  morality  was  demonstrable  in  a  manner  analogous  to  that  of  mathe- 
matics, he  held  that  the  abstract  cognitions  thus  obtained  possessed  in 
themselves  no  motive  force,  and  moreover  lacked  the  essential  element  of 
obligatoriness  until  they  were  brought  into  relation  to  the  divine  will. 
On  the  other  hand,  it  was  equally  vital  to  his  position  that  the  content 
of  the  divine  will  is  to  this  extent  ascertainable  by  the  use  of  reason.  I 
can  find  no  basis  whatever  for  the  suggestion  that  moral  distinctions  were 
at  times  regarded  by  him  as  the  products  of  arbitrary  will,  or  for  the  view 
that  the  nature  of  virtue  was  sometimes  thought  to  be  determined  by  the 
feeling  which  he  took  to  be  the  only  possible  motive  for  its  pursuit.  In 
his  account  of  "the  content  of  Locke's  rationalistic  ethics,"  Dr.  Lam- 
precht distinguishes  three  forms  of  his  theory,  according  to  which  morality 
is  based  on  (1)  The  consideration  of  mixed  modes  ;  (2)  The  Law  of  Nature  ; 
(3)  The  idea  of  God.  But  here,  again,  (1)  and  (3)  were  not  for  Locke 
alternative  theories,  but  complementary  aspects  of  any  complete  moral 
doctrine,  while  the  very  conception  of  a  Law  of  Nature  implied  for  him 
that  it  was  both  ascertainable  by  reason  and  an  expression  of  the  divine 
will. 

When  we  pass  from  Locke's  ethics  to  his  social  and  political  philosophy, 
the  materials  become  of  course  much  more  ample.  Dr.  Lamprecht  de- 
votes separate  chapters  to  Locke's  conception  of  the  State  of  Nature,  his 
theory  of  political  society  and  his  views  concerning  toleration  and  punish- 
ment. Of  each  of  these  he  gives  a  clear  and  adequate  account. 

J.  G. 


NEW   BOOKS.  113 


Received  also  : — 


S.   Alexander,    Spinoza  and  Time,   London,   G.   Allen  &   Unwin,   Ltd., 

1921,  pp.  80. 
W.  Windelband,  An  Introduction  to  Philosophy,  translated  by  J.  McCabe, 

London,  T.  Fisher  Unwin,  Ltd. ,  1921,  pp.  365. 
E.  Bevan,  Hellenism  and  Christianity,  London,  G.  Allen  &  Unwin,  Ltd., 

1921,  pp.  275. 
H.    Hb'ffding,    Bemerkungen  iiber   den  platonischen  Dialog  Parmenides, 

Berlin,  L.  Simion  Nf.,  1921,  pp.  56. 

B.  Bosanquet,    The  Meeting  of  Extremes  in  Contemporary  Philosophy, 

London,  Macmillan  &  Co.,  Ltd.,  1921,  pp.  xxviii,  220. 

C.  A.  Strong,  The  Wisdom,  of  the  Beasts,  London,  Constable  &  Co.,  Ltd., 

1921,  pp.  ix,  76. 
M.  De  Unamuno,  The  Tragic  Sense  of  Life  in  Men  and  in  Peoples,  trans. 

by    J.     E.    C.    Flitch,    London,    Macmillan  &  Co.,    Ltd.,   1921, 

pp.  xxxv,  332. 
S.  Pagani,  Programma  di  Bellagio,  Lugano,  Casa  Editrice  del  Coenobium, 

1920,  pp.  316. 

G.    Rensi,    Lineamenti  di  Fllosofia   Scettica,    2nd   Edition,   revised  and 

enlarged,  Bologna,  N.  Zanichelli,  1921,  pp.  442. 
C.  Guastella,  Le  Ragione  del  Fenomenismo,  Vol.  I. ,  Palermo,  E.  Priullar 

1921,  pp.  869. 

A.  Renda,  La  Validita  della  Keligione,  Citta  di  Castello,  Casa  Editrice  II 

"  Solco,"  1921,  pp.  271. 
E.  Meyerson,  De  I' Explication  dans  les  Sciences,  2  vols.,  Paris,  Payot  et> 

Cie,  1921,  pp.  xiv,  338 ;  469. 
G.   Urbain,   Les  Disciplines  d'une   Science   (Encyclopedic   Scientifique),. 

Paris,  G.  Doin,  1921,  pp.  325. 
J.  Pacotte,  La  Physique  Theorique  Nouvelle,  Paris,  Gauthier-Villars  et 

Cie,  1921,  pp.  vii,  182. 
M.  Franck,  La  Loi  de  Newton  est  la  Loi  Unique,  Paris,  Gauthier-Villars 

et  Cie,  1921,  pp.  158. 
J.    Lemaire,  Etude  sur  la  Connaissance  sensible  des  Objets  Exttrieurs, 

Liege,  Societe  Industrielle  d'Arts  et  Metiers,  1921,  pp.  57. 
The   Fourth   Dimension  Simply    Explained,    A    Collection    of    Essays, 

with   an   Introduction    and   Notes   by  H.   P.    Manning,   London, 

Methuen  &  Co.,  Ltd.,  1921,  pp.  251. 
Relativity  and  Gravitation,  edited  by  J.  M.  Bird,  London,  Methuen  & 

Co.,  Ltd.,  Il-t21,  pp,  xiv,  345. 
J.    Kremer,  Einstein  und  die   Weltanschauung 'skrisis,   Graz  und  Wienr 

"  Styria,"  1921,  pp.  59. 
P.    E.  More,  The  Religion  of  Plato,  Princeton  University  Press,  1921, 

pp.  xii,  352. 

E.  E.  Thomas,  Lotze's  Theory  of  Reality,  London,  Longmans,  Green  & 

Co.,  1921,  pp.  1,  217. 

Histoire  de  la  Nation  Francaise,  Tome  XII.,  Histoire  des  Lettres,  Vol.  /., 
par  J.  Bedier,  A.  Jeanroy  et  F.  Picavet,  Paris,  Plon-Nourrit  et 
Cie,  1921,  pp.  590. 

J.  Chevalier,  Descartes  (Les  Maitres  de  la  Pensee  Fran9aise),  Paris,  Plon- 
Nourrit  et  Cie,  1921,  pp.  vii,  362. 

F.  Nicolardot,  Apropos  de  Bergson,  Paris,  J.  Vrin,  1921,  pp.  174. 

E.  Brehier,  Histoire  de  la  Philosophic  allemande,  Paris,  Payot  et  Cie> 

1921,  pp.  160. 
E.   Aries,   L'Oeuvre  Scientifique  de  Sadi   Carnot}  Paris,   Payot  et   Cie, 

pp.  160. 

8 


114  NEW  BOOKS. 

F.  Florentine,  Manuale  di  Storia  della  Filosqfia,  a  Cura  di  G.  Mocticelli, 

2  vols.,  Turin,  G.  B.  Paravia  &  Co.,  1921,  pp.  xv,  318  ;  38*. 
R.  Stolzle,   Darwins    Stellung  zum    Gottescilauben,   Leipzig,  F.   Meiner, 

1922,  pp.  34. 
O.  Kraus,  Franz  Brentano,  zur  Kenntnis  seines  Lebens  und  seiner  Lehre, 

mib  Beitragen  von  Carl  Stumpf  und  E.  Husserl,  Munich,  O.  Beck, 

1919,  pp.  x,  171. 
S.    Dasgupta,    The   Study   af  Pataiijali,    University  of   Calcutta,   1920, 

pp.  ii,  207. 

G.  Dandoy,  An  Essay  on  the  Doctrine  of  the  Unreality  of  the  World  in  the 

Advaita,  Calcutta,  A.  Rome,  1919,  pp.  65. 

L.  T.  Hobhouae,  The  Elements  of  Social  Justice,  London,  G.  Allen  & 
Unwin,  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  208. 

A.  C.  Pigou,  The  Political  Economy  of  War,  London,  Macmillan  &  Co., 
Ltd.,  1921,  pp.  ix,  251. 

R.  De  la  Sizeranne,  RusJcin  e  la  Eeligione  della  Bellezza,  trans,  by 
B.  Reynaldi,  Turin,  G.  B.  Paravia "&  Co.,  1921,  pp.  viii,  265. 

K.  Koffka,  Die  Grundlagen  der  Psychischen  Entwicklung,  eim  Einfiihrung 
in  die  Kinderpsycholociie,  Osterwieck  am  Harz,  A.  W.  Ziekfeldt, 
1921,  pp.  vii,  278. 

M.  Kaufmann-Halle,  Die  Bcwusstseins-Vorgange  bei  Suggestion  nnd 
Hypnose,  Halle,  C.  Marhold,  1921,  pp.  36. 

>S.  Naccarati,  The  Morphologic  Aspect  of  Intelligence  (Archives  of  Psy- 
chology, No.  45),  New  York,  G.  E.  Stechert  &  Co.,  1921,  pp.  44.' 

J.  H.  Leuba,  The  Belief  in  God  and  Immortality,  2nd  edition,  Chicago, 
Open  Court  Publishing  Co.,  1921,  pp.  xxviii,  333. 

W.  H.  B.  Stoddart,  Mind  and  its  Disorders,  4th  edition,  London,  H.  K. 
Lewis  &  Co.,  Ltd.,  1921,  pp.  xiii,  592. 

A.  Hoch,  Benign  Stupors,  A  Study  of  a  New  Manic- Depressive  Reaction- 
Type,  Cambridge  University  Press,  1921,  pp.  xi,  284. 

J.  C.  Fliigel,  The  Psycho- Analytic  Study  of  the  Family  (International 
Psycho-Analytical  Library,  No.  3),  London,  International  Psycho- 
Analytical  Press,  1921,  pp.  x,  259. 

O.  Pfister,  Psycho -Analysis  in  the  Service  of  Ed-uratinn,  London,  H. 
Kimpton,  1922,  pp.  xii,  176. 

C.  W.  Valentine,  Dreams  and  the  Unconscious,  An  Introduction  to  the 
Study  of  Psycho-Anatysis,  London,  Christophers,  1921,  pp.  144. 

H.  Crichton  Miller,  The  New  Psychology  and  the  Teacher,  London, 
Jarrolds  Ltd.,  pp.  232. 

G.  Compayre,  L 'Adolescenza  :  Studi  di  Psicologia  e  Pedagogia,  Turin, 
G.  B.  Paravia  &  Co.,  1921,  pp.  xii,  125. 

0.  Capponi,  Pensieri  sulla  Educazione,  Turin,  G.  B.  Paravia  &  Co.,  1920, 

pp.  114. 
R.   S.    Woodworth,   Psychology :   A   Study  of  Mental   Life,  New   York, 

H.  Holt  &  Co  ,  1921,  pp.  x,  580. 
S.  S.  Brierley,  An  Introduction  to  Psychology,  London,  Methueii  &  Co., 

Ltd.,  1921,  pp.  vii,  152. 
M.  Ginsberg,  The  Psychology  of  Society,  London,  Methuen  &  Co.  Ltd., 

1921,  pp.  xvi,  174. 
T.  W.  Mitchell,   The  Psychology  of  Medicine,  London,  Methuen  &  Co. 

Ltd.,  1921,  pp.  vii,  U7. 
R.  H.  Hingley,   Psycho- Analysis,  London,  Methuen   &   Co.  Ltd.,  1921, 

pp.  vii,  190. 

1.  G.  Briggs,  Epilepsy,  Hysteria,  and  Neurasthenia,  London,  Methuen  & 

v.  Co.  Ltd.,  1921,  pp.  xi,  149. 


VIII.— PHILOSOPHICAL  PERIODICALS. 

BRITISH  JOURNAL  OF  PSYCHOLOGY.  Vol.  x.,  Part  4,  July,  1920. 
S.  Wyatt  and  H.  C.  Weston  contribute  a  paper  on  *A  Performance 
Test  under  Industrial  Conditions '.  [A  report  to  th°>  Fatigue  Research 
Board.]  The  test,  applied  to  a  group  of  cotton  operatives,  was  made 
to  resemble  closely  the  operations  involved  in  bobbin-winding  and  was 
continued  for  four  weeks.  The  results  gained  bear  chiefly  upon  the 
method  and  value  of  such  investigations.  The  authors  concluded  that 
the  time  required  to  perform  a  given  task  is  the  resultant  of  many  factors 
besides  fatigue,  and  the  effects  of  fatigue  may  be  considerably  reduced  or 
even  entirely  hidden  by  the  effects  of  these  other  influences.  Fatigue 
can  only  be  clearly  indicated  when  it  has  developed  to  such  an  extent  as 
to  become  the  dominant  factor  in  the  complex  situation.  Even  though 
the  operations  involved  in  the  test  are  similar  to  those  which  the  winders 
are  in  the  habit  of  performing  in  the  course  of  the  ordinary  winding 
operations,  about  three  weeks  must  elapse  before  the  winders  become 
adapted  to  the  test  conditions.  The  effects  of  practice  are  distinctly 
noticeable  throughout  the  test  period,  and  the  least  variation  from  the 
usual  conditions  of  labour  has  a  disturbing  effect  upon  the  results.  Great 
individual  differences  appear  even  among  four  workers  tested.  The 
results  appear  to  become  more  uniform  and  similar  as  the  test  progresses, 
but  the  afternoon  results  seem  to  be  more  irregular  than  those  of  the 
morning.  Thus  individual  differences  decrease  as  the  result  of  practice, 
but  the  day's  work  has  a  variable  effect  upon  different  individuals.  As  a 
means  of  indicating  the  amount  of  fatigue  produced  in  any  individual  by 
the  industrial  conditions  under  consideration,  the  test  is  useless.  The 
following  variable  disturbing  factors  became  evident ;  (ct)  variations  in 
illumination  at  the  time  of  the  test,  which  may  more  than  neutralise  the 
indications  of  fatigue  ;  (6)  variations  in  humidity  and  temperature  and  air 
movements  ;  (c)  variations  in  the  mood  of  the  individual  :  disturbing 
thoughts,  of  worries  or  of  pleasure,  may  hinder  work  ;  (d)  nervousness 
in  an  operative  caused  by  presence  of  an  investigator.  B.  Muscio  in 
4  Fluctuations  in  Mental  Efficiency,'  [another  report  to  the  Industrial 
Fatigue  Research  Board],  concludes,  as  the  result  of  experiments  on 
medical  and  other  students,  that  the  capacity  to  perform  various  mental 
tests  (involving  a  continuous  demand  on  voluntary  attention)  may  vary  in 
any  given  individual  at  different  times  independently  of  his  working  or 
restirjg,  and  that  these  variations  are  probably  different  for  different 
capacities,  suggesting  varying  organic  rhythms.  At  the  same  time  it 
seemed  evident  that  academic  study  did  lower  the  capacity  for  inter- 
polated tests  involving  continuous  attention,  such  as  the  crossing  out 
of  certain  selected  figures  in  a  page  of  figures,  each  in  a  special 
way.  The  other  papers  in  the  number,  which  are  short,  are  as 
follows :  J.  E.  Turner,  *  Note  on  Professor  J.  Laird's  Treatment 
of  Sense  Presentations ' ;  J.  Laird,  '  Reply  to  Mr.  J.  E.  Turner's 
Note '  ;  William  Platt,  '  Two  Examples  of  Child-Music '  ;  Ernest 
W.  Braendle,  « A  Voice  Reaction  Key '  (with  One  Diagram)  ;  William 


116  PHILOSOPHICAL    PEEIODICALS. 

McClelland,  '  The  Distribution  and  Reliability  of  Psychological  and 
Educational  Measurements';  Godfrey  H.  Thomson,  'The  General 
Factor  Fallacy  in  Psychology'.  Vol.  xi.,  Part  1,  October  1920. 
Five  writers  contribute  a  symposium  on  'Mind  and  Medium  in  Art,' 
presented  at  the  Congress  of  Philosophy  in  Oxford,  September,  1920. 
Charles  Marriott  sets  forth  the  theory  that  the  true  criterion  of  beauty  is 
the  appropriate  use  of  the  material  handled.  The  artistic  creation  "  must 
be  adapted  to  the  material  in  which  it  is  represented  and  to  the  con- 
venience of  the  hand  in  using  that  material.  Thus,  we  expect  a  broader 
treatment  of  landscape  in  water-colour  than  in  oils  because  the,  so  to 
speak,  'natural  '  play  of  water-colour  is  in  broad  washes."  For  him 
practical  and  aesthetic  reasons  are  at  bottom  the  same  thing.  The  writer 
claims  that  his  view  has  the  advantage  that  it  abolishes  all  the  dis- 
tinctions between  one  art  and  another  on  the  grounds  of  the  repre- 
sentation or  non-representation  of  nature,  and  also  that  it  abolishes  all 
the  artificial  and  uncertain  distinctions  between  various  forms  of  the  same 
art,  such  as  decorative  or  pictorial  painting,  realistic  or  romantic  poetry 
or  drama.  The  distinction  between  one  art  and  another  lies  in  the- 
material  used — words  being  the  "  material  "  of  literature.  A.  B.  Walkley 
criticises  this  view  of  art  as  being  an  external  one,  and  supports  the 
expressionist  theory  of  Croce.  even  to  the  extent  that  beauty  exists  to  the 
fullest  degree  in  the  mind  of  the  artist  before  the  material  object  is. 
created.  Henry  J.  Watt  argues  for  the  essentiality  of  a'basis  of  sensory 
beauty  in  any  work  of  art :  he  draws  upon  music  for  many  illustrations- 
and  criticises  equally  the  utilitarian  tendency  of  Marriott  and  the 
"nerveless  abstractions"  of  Croce,  supported  by  Walkley.  Edward 
Buliough  emphasises  the  distinction  between  art  in  its  static  aspect 
— the  objective  world  of  art — and  art  in  its  dynamic  aspect,  i.e.,  in 
artistic  creation  and  aesthetic  appreciation.  The  connecting  link  between 
the  medium  (material)  and  the  vision  of  the  artist  is  technique — the 
"adaptation  of  the  medium  to  the  vision".  The  vision  must  be  con- 
ceived in  terms  of  the  medium,  which  therefore  must  profoundly  affect 
the  artist ;  but  the  farther  his  artistic  imagination  breaks  away  from  the 
tradition  of  his  art  and  becomes  more  and  more  his  inner  personal 
creation,  the  deeper  and  the  more  sweeping  the  changes  which  the 
simultaneously  growing  power  of  his  technical  imagination  introduces 
into  his  handling  of  the  medium.  Thus  new  technical  processes,  new 
tools  and  methods,  new  ways  of  achieving  effects  and  new  solutions  of 
material  difficulties  are  discovered  and  minister  in  their  turn  to  the 
wealth  of  his  artistic  imagination.  C.  W.  Valentine  emphasises  the 
complexity  of  aesthetic  appreciation.  The  views  of  Marriott  and  Walkley 
(with  Croce)  like  most  theories  of  the  beautiful,  err  in  selecting  only  one 
aspect  of  the  beautiful,  which  is  inadequate,  though  true  so  far  as  it  goes. 
Croce  underestimates  the  importance  of  the  direct  appeal  made  to  us  by 
such  sensory  elements  as  sounds  and  colours,  apart  from  creative  activity 
in  the  appreciator.  In  many  cases  such  stimulus  from  without  is 
essential,  and  even  the  artist  often  embodies  his  imaginations  in  a 
medium  not  only  to  communicate  them  to  others  but  to  make  his  own 
aesthetic  experience  more  complete.  Five  papers  on  the  subject  '  Is 
Thinking  Merely  the  Action  of  Language  Mechanisms'  (another  sym- 
posium at  the  Oxford  Conference)  are  contributed  by  F.  C.  Bartlett  and 
E.  M.  Smith,  Godfrey  H.  Thomson,  T.  H.  Pear,  Arthur  Robinson, 
and  John  B.  Watson.  The  number  also  includes  the  following  papers  : 
J.  C.  Fliigel,  '  On  Local  Fatigue  in  the  Auditory  System  ' ;  Daniel  J. 
Collar,  '  A  Statistical  Survey  of  Arithmetical  Ability ' ;  W.  T.  Waughr 
'The  Causes  of  the  War  in  Current  Tradition';  Henry  J.  Watt,  'A 
Theory  of  Binaural  Hearing  '. 


PHILOSOPHICAL   PEEIODICALS.  117 

INTERNATIONAL  JOURNAL  OF  ETHICS.  Vol.  xxxi.,  No.  1.  October,  1920. 
M.  C.  Otto.  'Morality  as  Coercion  or  Persuasign.'  [Oppo-es  Prof. 
McGiivary's  conclusion  that  might  makes  right,  but  maintains  relativity 
of  morality.  Emphasises  distinction  between  persuasion,  in  which  the 
compelling  force  is  exercised  by  the  ideal  itself,  and  coercion  in  which  it  is 
exercised  by  something  external.  The  writer  concludes  that  the  funda- 
mental problem  of  morality  is  to  secure  the  richest  total  of  satisfied  desire, 
and  that  the  application  of  intelligence  by  way  of  adjustment  among 
conflicting  ideals  promises  a  better  issue  than  warfare.]  T.  H.  Proctor. 
'The  Motives  of  the  Soldier.'  [An  estimate  of  the  motives  which  (1) 
induced  the  citizen  to  become  a  soldier  and  (2)  sustained  him  during  the 
protracted  war,  and  of  the  effects  of  war  on  him  as  an  ex-service  citizen. 
States  that  though  English  moral  standard  was  exceedingly  high  few  were 
influenced  by  it,  and  that  fear  was  the  predominant  motive  in  the  majority 
of  cases  ;  in  warfare  soldier  sustained  by  fear  and  esprit  de  corps ;  as  a 
result  of  war  left  infinitely  poorer  morally  and  drained  emotionally.] 
Rupert  Clendon  Lodge.  'Plato  and  the  Judge  of  Conduct.'  [Attempts 
to  harmonise  views  of  Cambridge  and  modern  Platonists  in  the  view  that 
everyone  philosophises,  some  more  than  others,  and  that  "  so  far  as  their 
judgment  is  philosophical  so  far  is  it  valuable".]  Ruth  M.  Gordon. 
'  Has  Mysticism  a  Moral  Value  ? '  [Emphasises  ego-centric  attitude  of 
many  mystics,  and  suggests  that  this  deprives  mysticism  of  value  through 
neglect  of  social  nature  of  morality  ;  admits  value  for  certain  individuals 
provided  that  it  is  not  complete.]  Henry  T.  Secrist.  '  Morale  and 
Morals.'  [A  brief  account  of  morale  in  the  war,  and  its  part  in  reinforcing 
morals  through  enlisting  compelling  force  of  morale  on  side  of  morals ; 
suggests  applications  to  civic  life.]  Eugene  W.  Lyman.  '  The  Ethics  of 
the  Wage  and  Profit  System.'  [Maintains  that  under  present  social 
conditions  the  enterpriser  is  privileged  in  the  economic  scheme,  below 
him  hierarchy  of  inequalities  of  opportunity  ;  if  supported  by  theory 
of  self-interest  as  only  economic  motive  reinforces  anti-social  motives ; 
"suggests  as  solution  socialising  of  economic  motive  and  democratising 
of  economic  method.]  No.  2.  January,  1921.  Frank  Chapman  Sharp. 
*  Some  Problems  of  Fair  Competition.'  [Assuming  that  fair  com-^ 
petition  is  seeking  success  by  offering  better  service  than  competitors, 
and  that  this  is  the  best  solution  of  the  double  problem  of  produc- 
ing the  maximum  desirable  of  goods  and  of  distributing  fairly,  dis- 
cusses inter  alia  problems  of  boycott,  special  rebates,  tying  clauses.] 
Victor  S.  Yarros.  'Is  there  a  Law  of  Human  Progress?'  [Suggests 
that  existence  of  ideals  and  of  efforts  to  attain  them  is  evidence  of 
progress,  maintains  that  modern  ideals  are  infinitely  higher  than  those 
of  Greece,  and  that  progress  is  characteristic  of  the  human  will — almost 
a  law.]  J.  E.  Turner.  'The  Genesis  and  Differentiation  of  the  Moral 
Absolute.'  [Advances  the  view  that  since  mind  is  a  whole,  discovering 
ideals,  each  at  first  an  absolute,  all  these  must  be  related  to  each  other 
and  to  the  all-inclusive  whole  ;  discusses  the  error  of  isolating  intellectual, 
.'esthetic  and  moral  ideals,  raising  the  problem  as  to  how  the  absoluteness 
of  an  all-inclusive  ethical  criterion  can  be  maintained,  and  suggests  that 
personality  as  an  absolute  within  the  Absolute,  in  touch  with  it  at  all  its  con- 
fines,, really  constitutes  the  basal  moral  criterion.]  I.  W.  Howerth.  '  The 
Labour  Problem  from  the  Social  Standpoint.'  [Shows  how  problem  is 
partially  apprehended  by  Labour,  Capital  and  Consumer  ;  maintains  that 
social  well-being  gives  the  only  complete  view  of  the  problem  of  supplying 
economic  needs  of  society  with  least  expenditure  of  time,  means  and 
energy,  and  that  progressive  solution  is  possible  by  elimination  of  un- 
necessary labour  through  legislation,  education  and  organisation  of  available 


118  PHILOSOPHICAL  PERIODICALS. 

working  power  thereby  making  labour  attractive.]  J.  D.  Stoops.  'The- 
Instinct  to  Workmanship  and  the  Will  to  Work. '  [Accepts  instincts  as 
basis  of  will  energy,  will  as  organisation  of  instincts,  emotions  and  senti- 
ments ;  shows  the  need  for  organisation  of  work  so  as  to  utilise  energy 
of  basic  instincts  and  to  develop  organised  personality ;  dissociation  of 
will  and  instincts  of  workmanship  and  property  involves  disorganisation, 
so  that  main  problem  is  discovery  of  inherited  capabilities  along  which 
fullest  development  of  personality  is  possible.]  Henry  S.  Curtis.  'The 
Mother's  Confessional.'  [Justifies  sympathetic  discussion  between  mother 
and  children  as  relieving  fears  and  reducing  unhappiness.]  Allan  L. 
Carter.  '  Schiller  and  Shaftesbury.'  [Shows  essential  similarity  derived 
from  Plato  in  doctrine  of  harmony  as  basic  principle,  and  in  general  attitude 
to  ethical  problems,  e.g.,  relation  to  art,  immediacy  of  moral  perception, 
jural  morality,  etc.  ;  discusses  main  divergences.]  No.  4.  July,  1921. 
Victor  S.  Yarros.  'Contemporary  American  Radicalism.'  [Upholds 
Radicalism — the  proposing  of  fundamental  far-reaching  measures — as 
inevitable  and  desirable  if  the  civilisation  of  America  is  to  be  saved  and 
that  of  Europe  cured,  particularly  with  reference  to  the  economic  system 
and  political  organisation  of  which  the  basic  ideals  are  civil  individual 
liberty  and  equality  of  economic  opportunity.]  Emile  Boutroux.  '  The 
Immediate  Future.'  [A  plea  for  universal  classical  education  for  the 
development  of  judgment,  of  moral  consciousness  and  sense  of  the  ideal, 
rather  than  of  immediately  utilisable  capacities,  in  order  to  maintain  on 
a  footing  of  equality  the  rights  of  nations  as  moral  individuals  despite 
inevitable  inequalities  in  extent  and  power.]  Henry  Nelson  Wieman. 
4  Personal  and  Impersonal  Groups. '  [Criticises  Prof.  J.  E.  Boodin's  view 
that  small  personal  groups  are  the  ultimate  units  of  civilisation ;  maintains 
dyadic  nature  of  human  welfare,  the  fulfilment  of  central  organised  ten- 
dencies and  of  peripheral  unrelated  tendencies,  involving  two  incommen- 
surable values,  the  one  spiritual  the  other  material ;  of  these  the  former  is 
increasing  in  importance  but  it  is  necessary  to  recognise  the  value  of  the 
impersonal.]  Claude  C.  H.  Williamson.  'Progress.'  [Maintains  that 
progress  is  not  a  law  of  human  history  but  is  product  of  persons  who  will 
to  serve,  that  there  is  continuity  in  the  process  of  change  within  the  whole, 
revealing  a  growth  in  value  ;  emphasises  importance  of  succession  of  men 
of  genius  as  condition  for  continuation  of  progress,  and  suggests  that 
Christian  view  of  progress  is  more  in  agreement  with  human  nature 
than  pessimism  or  an  optimism  regarding  progress  as  automatic.]  John 
H.  Mecklin.  'The  Philosopher  as  Social  Interpreter.'  [Holds  that 
American  philosophers  enjoying  the  quiet  backwaters  of  philosophic 
calm  are  largely  responsible  for  present  moral  bankruptcy  and  aimlessness 
of  American  life  ;  suggests  that  they  need  to  live  '  in  rapport '  with  their 
fellows,  to  cultivate  the  historical  attitude  and  to  study  immediately 
pressing  social  problems,  piecemeal,  if  necessary,  leaving  till  later  the  task 
of  synthesis.]  Benjamin  Ives  Oilman.  'Death  Control.'  [Analyses 
reasons  why  few  can  face  the  problem  deliberately  and  suggests  that  with 
spread  of  belief  in  Being  of  universe  a  rational  hastening  of  death  as 
solution  of  problem  would  be  viewed  in  hopeful  expectancy.]  E.  A. 
Burtt.  'Present-day  Tendencies  in  Ethical  Theory.'  [Treats  question 
as  to  relativity  or  absoluteness  of  moral  judgments  and  standards  as 
outstanding  question  ;  if  approached  from  ethical  standpoint,  relativity 
appears  inevitable,  if  from  universal  point  of  view  tendency  towards 
absolutist  position,  either  materialistic  or  idealistic;  alternative,  prag- 
matic standpoint  attempting  compromise  between  relativity  and  uni- 
versality, with  ethical  standard  a  type  of  continuity  inherent  in  the 
structure  of  things.] 


PHILOSOPHICAL   PEPJODICALS.  119 

REVUE   DE   PHILOSOPHIE.      January-February,    1921.     Th.    Mainage. 

'.L'Histoire  des  Religions  a  1'Institut  Catholique  de  Paris.'  [Address 
delivered  at  the  opening  of  a  new  course  on  the  comparative  history  of 
religions.  The  address  contains  a  discussion  of  the  principles  of  Evolu- 
tionism in  religion.  The  thesis  maintained  is  that  Evolutionism  is  false, 
because  there  was  no  evolution  in  religion.  The  plan  of  the  new  course 
is  mapped  out.]  R.  Guenon.  '  Le  Theosophisme  :  Histoire  d'une  pseudo- 
religion.'  [Theosophism,  not  theosophy,  the  true  name  for  the  professions 
of  the  '  Theosophical  Society '.  Details  about  the  origins  of  the  Society 
given  to  supplement  those  in  a  previous  article  in  this  review.  They 
chiefly  concern  the  relations  of  this  with  other  societies  of  a  more  or  less 
occult  character.]  P.  Vignon.  *  Pour  la  philosophic  des  etres  naturels. 
Interpretation  aristotelicienne  de  1'atomisme  contemporain.'  (Conclusion.) 
[A  rapid  and  condensed  summary  of  the  conclusions  reached  by  the  author 
in  the  preceding  articles.]  Q.  Voisine.  *  Un  nouveau  traite  de  Logique. 
(Fin.)1  [M.  Goblot  (the  author  reviewed)  says  (a)  that  all  induction  is 
based  on  our  confidence  in  determinism ;  (b)  that  determinism  supposes 
the  constancy  and  universality  of  order,  without  the  possibility  of  excep- 
tions, although  the  possibility  of  belief  in  miracles,  etc.,  shows  that  deter- 
minism is  a  postulate  and  not  a  self-evident  principle  ;  (c)  that,  if  miracles,, 
free  will,  etc.,  are  possible,  induction  is  impossible  ;  (d)  that  finality  does 
not  suppose  an  intelligence.  These  positions  attacked.  In  induction  we 
presuppose  the  existence  of  natures  (this  idea  being  formed  from  experi- 
ence). The  process  of  induction  consists  in  discovering  the  laws  according 
to  which  these  natures  act.  A  law  is  a  rule  for  the  activity  of  a  being, 
and  in  its  metaphysical  basis  is  unchangeable,  but  it  does  not  apply  except 
under  definite  circumstances.  Miracles,  etc.,  do  not  affect  the  law  but 
alter  the  circumstances.  The  natures  have  definite  tendencies — hence 
finality,  which  may  be  conscious  (intelligent)  or  unconscious.  The  latter 
presupposes  an  outside  intelligence.  Finality,  properly  understood,  does 
riot  exist  without  an  intelligence.]  F.  Peillaube.  'Inauguration  de 
deux  nouvelles  chaires  a  la  Faculte  de  Philosophic  de  1'Universite  libre 
de  Paris.'  [Report  of  the  author  (Dean  of  the  Faculty)  presented  at  the 
inauguration  of  the  chairs  of  Droit  nature!  and  Principes  chretiens  du  droit 
des  c/en*,  founded  by  the  '  Fondation  des  morts  de  la  guerre  a  1'Universite 
Catholique  de  Paris'.]  Th.  Greenwood.  'LeCongresde  Philosophic 
d'Oxford.'  [First  part  of  an  account  of  the  congress  of  September,  1920. 
The  author  takes  the  papers  and  discussions  in  turn,  gives  their  substance 
and  occasionally  adds  a  short  criticism.]  March- April,  1921.  R.  Guenon. 
'  Le  Theosophisme :  Histoire  d'une  pseudo- religion  (Suite).'  [The  basis  of 
all  theosophism  is  the  MahAtmas  or  "  masters  ".  For  the  esoteric  section 
the  occult  phenomena  are  also  essential.  IVJme.  Blavatsky's  influence  and 
power  of  suggestion  described.  Her  so-called  Esoteric  Buddhism  is  a 
medley  of  misunderstood  Neo-platonisrn,  Gnosticism,  Jewish  Cabala, 
Hermetism,  Occultism,  with  scraps  of  Oriental  doctrines,  all  grouped 
round  two  or  three  ideas  of  modern  and  purely  Western  origin.  The 
principal  heads  of  theosophical  teaching  are  :  (i)  Evolution,  fantastically 
worked  out,  including  (ii)  Re-incarnation.  (Both  ideas,  in  the  author's 
opinion,  of  quite  modern  origin.)  (iii)  The  law  of  karma  (  =  retribution — 
a  mistranslation).  Theosophism  and  similar  systems  unbalance  the  mind 
and  are  therefore  a  real  danger.  Theosophism  also  discredits  Oriental 
doctrines  with  Europeans,  and  the  Western  intellect  with  Orientals.} 
G.  Fournier.  '  L'Influence  de  Coleridge  sur  Stuart  Mill  dans  le  probleme 
de  la  Necessite  et  de  la  Liberte.'  [J.  S-  Mill  followed  Coleridge  in  re- 
jecting the  social  theories  of  Hobbes  and  Rousseau,  and  in  looking  to 
history  for  the  method  of  reconciling  necessity  and  liberty.  Necessity 
rules  the  average,  liberty  accounts  for  individual  divergences.  Mill's 


120  PHILOSOPHICAL    PEKIODICALS. 

theory  expounded.]  A.  Dies.  'Revue  Critique  d'Histoire  de  la  Philo- 
sophic antique.'  [Conclusion  of  an  article,  of  which  the  last  instalment 
was  in  April  1913.  Short  notices  of  thirty-nine  books  in  various  languages, 
on  Plato,  Aristotle,  and  later  philosophers.]  F.  Monnies.  *  Le  Desir  du 
Bonheur  et  1'Existence  de  Dieu.'  [Discussion  of  the  argument  for  the 
existence  of  God  drawn  from  the  desire  of  happiness.  The  author  gives 
his  version  of  the  argument  and  then  shows  the  invalidity  of  two  other 
forms,  viz.,  the  argument  based  on  the  desire  of  the  Supreme  Good,  and 
the  argument  from  Immanence.  His  argument  is :  Happiness  is  the 
object  of  a  natural  desire  in  man.  (Terms  defined,  and  proposition 
established  from  experience.)  A  natural  desire  cannot  be  vain.  ((i)  Es- 
tablished a  priori  from  the  premiss  that  everything  is  capable  of 
explanation,  and  (ii)  confirmed  by  analogy  with  natural  tendencies  in 
plants  and  animals — there  exists  that  whereby  these  tendencies  can  be 
satisfied.)  For  the  explanation  of  this  desire  a  future  life  and  a  Bene- 
volent Intelligent  Providence  are  required.  The  argument  does  not  lead 
to  the  existence  of  God  as  the  Supreme  Good.]  Th.  Greenwood.  '  Le 
Coiigres  d'Oxford  (Suite).'  [In  this  part  the  author  limits  himself  usually 
to  a  report  of  the  discussions,  lie  ends  by  remarking  an  absence  of  com- 
mon ground  in  philosophical  discussions,  and  a  connexion  between  natural 
sciences  and  modern  philosophy.]  May-June,  1921.  P.  Doncceur.  '  Le 
Nominalisme  d'Occam  :  Theories  du  mouvement,  H  u  temps  et  du  lieu. '  [The 
Scholastics  held  movement  to  be  transitm  a  potentia  in  actum,  a  reality 
which  is  neither  pure  act  nor  pure  potency.  Occam  explains  it  as  ''a  form 
acquired  part  by  part  and  connoting  the  negation  of  all  parts  still  to 
follow  ".  With  him  it  is  not  a  physical  reality  but  a  logical  concept.  He 
identifies  Time  with  movement,  and  he  identifies  Place  with  the  body 
occupying  the  place  and  defiiiing  its  own  bounds  '  by  not  extending  its 
parts  further '.]  R.  (iuenon.  '  Le  Theosophisme  :  Histoire  d'une  pseudo- 
religion  (Suite).  [The  history  of  theosophism  traced  from  the  advent  to 
power  of  Mrs.  Besant,  through  the  attempts  to  educate  new  "messiahs," 
and  to  found  propagandist  associations  such  as  the  '  Order  of  the  Star  in 
the  East,'  up  to  the  latest  connexion  between  the  notorious  Mr.  Lead- 
beater  and  the  'Old  Catholic'  Bishop  A.  H.  Mathew.]  J.  Pacheu. 
*  L'Ecole  clu  Coeur.'  [The  phrase  means  commonly  the  practice  of  spirit- 
uality in  order  to  remove  disorderly  affections.  But  the  heart  may  be 
more  strictly  a  s:-hool,  since  love  and  knowledge  of  God  interact,  love 
giving  light  and  light  stimulating  love.  This  seen  especially  in  mystical 
union,  which  is  wholly  one  of  will,  yet  thereby  the  understanding  is  en- 
lightened beyond  its  natural  powers.]  B.  Romeyer.  'L'ldee  de  la 
Verite  dans  la  Philosophic  de  S.  Augustin.'  [Review  of  a  book  by  Ch. 
Boyer.  Everything  exists  as  either  Pure  or  participated  Being.  Our 
mind,  since  it  has  to  conform  to  its  objects  and  is  therefore  inferior  to 
them,  can  have  only  participated  being.  Its  objects,  in  turn,  must  either 
be  Pure  or  participated  beings.  Hence  ultimately  we  are  led  to  God. 
Knowledge  is  a  participated  expression  of  the  Divine  Ideas.  'Participa- 
tion 5  secures  alike  against  Pantheism  and  Ontologism.  But,  do  not  the 
Principle  of  Sufficient  Reason,  and  the  Causa  Exemplar  is  offer  an 
«ven  more  fundamental  explanation?]  P.  Vignon.  'La  Philosophic 
de  I'Organisme. '  [A  favourable  review  of  the  French  translation  of 
H.  Driesch's  well-known  book.]  A.  Ancel.  '  L'lnfluence  de  la  Volonte 
sur  riutelligence  dans  1'Exercice  de  la  Pensee  et  1' Adhesion  an  Vrai.' 
[The  will  can  and  must  influence  the  intelligence  in  a-sent  whenever 
there  is  not  complete  intrinsic  evidence.  The  act  is  legitimate  if  con- 
fined to  compelling  assent,  not  if  extended  to  affecting  the  nature  or  firni- 
tieas  of  assent.]  July-August,  1921.  X.  Moisant.  'La  Bienveil- 
lance  Divine  d'apres  Saint  Thomas.'  [An  exposition  of  St.  Thomas' 


PHILOSOPHICAL   PEBIODICALS.  121 

teaching  on  the  Benevolentia  Dei — the  Divine  Will  loving  His 
Creatures.  The  author  explains  the  opposition  between  the  Divine 
Benevolence  and  the  human  ideal  of  a  selfless  love,  of  an  unlimited  and 
impartial  bestowal  of  benefits.  The  fact  that  the  Creator  is  the  end  of 
"the  Creature  reconciles  all  contradictions  (Theocentrism).  On  St.  Thoma$' 
theory  the  love  of  self  is  not  denied,  nor  judged  to  be  evil  (Ecstatic 
theory),  but  is  included  in  the  love  of  God  (Physical  theory).  Man,  in 
seeking  good,  is  seeking  God ;  though  the  Fall  has  blinded  him  to  his 
true  end.  The  author  also  shows  how  God's  love  surpasses  the  human 
ideal  in  efficacity,  disinterestedness  and  other  qualities.]  R.  Gu6non, 
f  Le  Theosophisme  (Suite  et  fin). '  [The  final  sections  of  this  account  deal 
with  the  relations  of  theosophism  with  the  various  branches  of  what  is 
called  '  irregular  '  Free-Masonry,  its  widespread  auxiliaries  among  humani- 
tarian, vegetarian,  and  pacificist  societies  of  all  classes,  and,  in  India,  its 
political  connexion  with  British  Imperialism.]  Th.  Greenwood.  'La 
Methode  Pelman.'  [Is  the  undeniable  success  of  Pelmanism  due  to  the 
intrinsic  value  of  its  methods  ?  By  a  detailed  analysis,  the  writer  shows 
that,  while  disclaiming  any  but  a  practical  role,  Pelmanism  is  employ- 
ing time-honoured  principles  of  Aristotelian  realist  philosophy.] 
H.  Amiard.  '  (Jne  refutation  du  Pantheisme.'  [Critique  in  praise 
of  Father  Valensin's  article  on  Pantheism  in  the  Dictionnaire  d'Apolo- 
gtiique,  commending  especially  his  clear  exposition  of  the  subject,  and  the 
soundness  and  originality  of  his  method  of  refutation.  For  the  latter, 
philosophical  Pantheism  is  distinguished  into  Pantheisme  savant  and 
Pantheisme  naif  according  as  it  has,  or  has  not,  taken  account  of  the 
difficulty  of  identifying  a  material  finite  world  with  a  spiritual  infinite 
God.  The  Pantlieisme  savant  cannot  be  refuted  a  priori  in  view  of  the 
Incarnation,  but  it  is  shown  to  be  unproved,  and  to  be  irreconcilable  with 
the  fact  that  God  and  individual  men  are  distinct  responsible  subjects.] 


IX.— NOTES. 
PROF.  BROAD  ON  THE  EXTERNAL  WORLD. 

MAY  I  state  a  difficulty  which  I  find  in  Prof.  Broad's  most  instructive 
paper  on  the  External  World  in  the  October  MIND  ? 

It  is,  if  I  understand  him  rightly,  a  point  which  I  discussed  in  my 
Logic,  ii.,  307.  But  he  does  not  carry  it  out  to  the  difficulty  which  I 
perhaps  wrongly  found.  The  question  is  whether  sensa  can  be  body- 
dependent  in  a  certain  high  degree,  being  partially  conditioned  by  the 
traces  left  in  the  body  by  past  experiences  (MiND,  pp.  391,  395)  without 
being  necessarily  mind- dependent  also. 

My  difficulty  (Logic,  I.e.}  was  that  a  bodily  response  of  this  kind,  in- 
volving the  operation  of  influences  from  past  experiences  which  are  active 
in  present  sensation,  cannot,  so  I  thought,  be  got  at  and  exhibited  except 
through  the  action  of  an.  organ  of  sense,  which  in  practice  is  necessarily  a 
mental  action.  I  said  that  if  you  could  get  at  the  response  of  the  eye  as- 
modified  by  the  bodily  conditions,  apart  from  the  visual  response,  you 
might  find  that  the  mental  side  of  the  visual  sensation  had  made  no  dif- 
ference to  what  the  bodily  conditions  gave.  But  the  idea  of  doing  this  is 
surely  chimerical.  And  so,  practically,  it  seems  to  me,  if  you  let  in  the 
bodily  traces  of  past  experience  as  modifying  the  sensa,  you  let  in  all  the 
modification  of  mental  response  that  has  been  included  under  apperception 
or  any  such  term. 

When  mere  external  bodily  position  is  in  question  (MiND,  p.  391)  I  can 
see  that  this  does  not  apply.  You  can  tell,  I  suppose,  how  the  look  of  the 
penny  must  alter  as  a  man  first  looks  at  it  direct  and  then  steps  away  to* 
one  side.  You  can  separate  that  bodily  effect  deductively,  so  to  speak. 
But  the  other  cases  on  page  391 — must  you  not  take  in  the  mental  response 
to  get  the  result  of  the  bodily  conditions  ? 

I  have  no  axe  to  grind — no  subjective  idealism  to  maintain — in  this 
argument.  If  my  thought  did  create  the  landscape  before  my  window — a 
notion  to  which  I  can  only  with  the  utmost  difficulty  attach  any  meaning 
whatever — still  the  landscape  would  be  there,  and  we  should  have  to- 
acknowledge  its  physical  determinations  and  connexions. 

But  the  point  in  question  did  puzzle  me,  and  I  should  be  glad  to  see  ifc 
explained. 

B.    BOSANQUET. 

I. AM  not  certain  whether  I  fully  understand  the  point  raised  by  Dr. 
iBosanquet  in  his  Note  on  my  paper  on  The  External  World.  On  referring 
to  the  passage  (Logic,  ii.,  p.  307), which  he  quotes,  I  see  that  he  is  there 
arguing  against  people  who  hold  that,  although  we  perceive  external 
things  through  the  medium  of  eyes,  ears,  etc.,  yet  this  medium  makes 
no  difference  to  the  object  perceived.  I  understand  this  to  be  Prof. 
Alexander's  view,  but  I  find  it  quite  as  incredible  as  Dr.  Bosanquet 
himself  does,  and  for  much  the  same  reasons. 

I  take  it  that  Dr.  Bosanquet  is  not  raising  this  point  in  his  Note.     I 


NOTES.  123 

understand  him  to  mean  one  or  both  of  the  following  closely  connected 
things  :  (i)  If  bodily  traces  be  part-conditions  of  our  sensa  they  are  no 
less  part-conditions  of  our  sense  awareness.  Now,  if  x  determines  both 
y  and  z  and  always  determines  both  together,  you  may  be  able  to  say  that 
z  does  depend  on  x,  but  you  have  no  right  to  say  that  »  does  not  depend  on 
y.  y  is  an  invariable  accompaniment  of  z  on  the  hypothesis  that  y  and  » 
are  both  invariable  accompaniments  of  x.  (Cf.  Mr.  Russell's  argument 
that  the  parallelist  who  denies  interaction  commits  an  inconsistency.) 
(ii)  After  all,  the  traces  are  hypothetical ;  what  you  can  actually  observe 
is  the  sensa  and  their  qualities  and  the  act  of  sensing.  Hence  it  is  closer 
to  the  facts  to  say  that  the  sensum  depends  in  part  on  the  mental  act 
than  to  say  that  it  depends  in  part  on  the  hypothetical  bodily  trace. 

If  this  be  Dr.  Bosanquet's  contention,  I  must  plead  guilty  ;  and  I 
cannot  at  present  offer  any  satisfactory  answer.  I  purposely  omitted  the 
question  of  the  physiological  conditions  of  sensation  so  far  as  I  could,  and 
no  complete  answer  to  Dr.  Bosanquet's  point  could  be  given  till  this 
question  has  been  properly  threshed  out.  At  present  I  find  it  most 
puzzling  ;  and  I  feel  that  no  philosopher,  Realist  or  Idealist,  has  tackled 
it  satisfactorily.  Perhaps  I  may  end  by  pointing  out  what  seem  to  me  the 
two  chief  difficulties  :  (i)  If  we  treat  our  bodies  as  a  kind  of  medium, 
they  are  a  medium  that  goes  everywhere  with  us,  and  therefore  we  cannot 
allow  for  their  effects.  Thus  the  supposed  sensa  in  places  where  there 
are  no  living  bodies  (on  such  a  theory  as  Russell's,  e.g.)  are  as  purely 
hypothetical  as  the  old  physical  object  conceived  as  a  cause  of  sensations. 
(ii)  Our  bodies  seem  partly  to  condition  the  sensa  themselves,  and  partly 
to  condition  what  goes  on  in  our  minds.  Can  we  draw  a  distinct  line 
anywhere  between  these  two  sets  of  effects  ?  How  far  does  what  happens 
in  my  body  simply  determine  thab  I  shall  sense  one  rather  than  another 
of  several  coexisting  sensa  ?  And  how  far  does  it  actually  determine  the 
properties  of  sensa  themselves  ?  I  imagine  that  these  are  the  kind  of 
questions  that  Dr.  Bosanquet  has  in  mind.  If  so,,  I  fully  admit  their 
importance,  and  can  only  say  that  I  wish  I  knew  how  to  answer  them. 

C.  D.  BROAD. 


DEATH  OF  M.  EMILE  BOUTROUX. 

BY  the  death  on  21st  November  of  M.  Emile  Boutroux  at  the  age  of 
seventy-six  the  world  is  deprived  of  a  philosopher  of  international  reputa- 
tion and  of  a  personality  beloved  and  respected  by  all  who  knew  him. 
Jjmile  Boutroux  was  born  at  Montrouge  (Seine)  in  1848,  and  entered  the 
Ecole  Normale  Superieure  in  1865.  In  1869  he  went  to  Heidelberg,  where 
he  worked  under  Zeller,  the  first  part  of  whose  History  of  Greek  Philo- 
sophy he  translated  later  into  French.  Boutroux  took  his  degree  at  the 
Sorbonne  in  1874,  presenting  as  his  thesis  a  work  entitled  De  la  Contin- 
yence  des  Lois  de  la  Nature.  This  work  was  first  published  in  1879,  when, 
however,  it  attracted  but  little  attention.  But  on  its  republication  in 
1895  it  was  recognised  as  containing  that  which  had  provided  the  point 
of  departure  for  the  speculation  of  Bergson  and  Le  Roy,  who  had  been 
Boutroux's  pupils,  and  it  has  since  gone  through  a  large  number  of 
editions,  besides  being  translated  into  the  other  principal  languages.  The 
volume  designated  De  Vide'e  de  loi  naturelle  dans  la  science  et  dans  la 
philosophic,  published  in  1895,  was  a  continuation  of  the  same  theme. 
Boutroux  was  the  author  of  many  other  works  dealing  especially  with  the 
history  of  philosophy.  In  1904  and  1905  he  was  Gilford  Lecturer  in 


124  NOTES. 

Glasgow,  where  he  lectured  in  French  on  La  Nature  et  V Esprit,  his  first 
course  being  on  "  Nature  "  and  his  second  on  "  Spirit  ".  These  lectures 
have  never  been  published;  but  a  portion  of  the  material  of  them  is  evidently 
embodied  in  the  book  on  Science  et  Religion  dans  la  philosophie  contem- 
poraine  which  appealed  in  French  in  1908,  and  in  English  in  1909.  As 
Professor  in  the  University  of  Paris,  a  position  to  which  he  was  appointed 
in  1888  and  which  he  resigned  a  few  years  ago,  he  exerted  considerable 
influence  upon  successive  generations  of  students  ;  and  as  Director  (since 
1902)  of  the  Fondatiou  Thiers  he  came  into  close  contact  with  a  large 
number  of  younger  men  who  were  engaged  in  original  research  of  a  philo- 
sophical kind.  The  death  in  1919  of  his  wife,  a  sister  of  Henri  Poincare, 
was  a  severe  blow  to  him,  but  he  retained  to  the  end  his  wonderful  vivacity 
and  charm  of  manner,  as  also  his  deep  interest  in  philosophical  problems 
and  social  affairs.  As  late  as  the  December  of  1914,  he  visited  England 
to  deliver  the  Hertz  lecture  at  the  British  Academy  on  "Certitude  and 
Truth  ".  This  lecture  was  reprinted  in  1916  with  a  number  of  other  essays 
in  a  volume  entitled  Philosophy  and  War — a  volume  in  which  there  is  no 
bitterness,  but  in  which  the  hope  is  repeatedly  expressed  that  the  Germany 
which  was  respected  and  admired  by  the  whole  world,  the  Germany  of 
Leibniz  and  Goethe,  may  yet  some  day  be  reborn. 

ERRATUM. 

The  Editor  regrets  that,  through  a  mistake  for  which  he  alone  is  to 
blame,  the  following  corrections  need  to  be  made  in  the  last  number  of 
MIND  and  in  the  Table  of  Contents  of  Vol.  XXX.  :— 
P.  498,  1.  16  from  bottom,  for  "Rivista  di  Filosofia   Neo-Scolastica  " 

read  "  Rivista  di  Filosofia". 

P.  499,  1.  3,  before  "Anno  xiii."  insert    "Rivista  di  Filosofia  Neo- 
Scolastica  ". 
Contents,  p.  viii,  after  1.  22  insert — 

Rivista  di  Filosofia  (xiii.  1 ;  Jan. -March,  1921)     .         .         .498 
and  for  1.  24  substitute 

Rivista  di   Filosofia  Neo-Scolastica   (xiii.   2  ;    March- April, 

1921) 500 


MIND  ASSOCIATION. 

The  following  is  the  full  list  of  the  officers  and  members, 
of  the  Association  : — 

OFFICEKS. 

President— PHOT?.  S.  ALEXANDER. 

Vice-Presidents— PROFS.  J.  B.  BAILLIE,  B.  BOSANQUET,  H.  WILDON 
CARR,  T.  CASE,  G.  DA  WES  HICKS,  F.  B.  JEVONS,  J.  H.  MUIR- 
HEAD,  A.  S.  PRINGLE-PATTISON,  C.  READ,  J.  A.  SMITH,  N.  KEMP 
SMITH,  W.  R.  SORLEY,  G.  F.  STOUT,  and  J.  WARD,  PRINCIPAL 
G.  GALLOWAY,  DR.  J.  M.  E.  McTAGGART,  and  THE  VERY  REV. 
DR.  HASTINGS  RASHDALL 

Editor— D-&.  G.  E.  MOORE. 

Treasurer— DR.  F.  C.  S.  SCHILLER. 

Secretary— Ma.  G.  R.  G.  MURE. 

Guarantors— THE  RIGHT  HON.  A.  J.  BALFOUR,  VISCOUNT  HALDANE., 
and  MRS.  HENRY  SIDGWICK. 

MEMBEES. 

ALEXANDER  (Prof.  S.),  The  University,  Manchester. 

ANDERSON  (J.),  Department  of  Philosophy,  The  University,  Edinburgh. 

ANDERSON  (Prof.  W.),  University  College,  Auckland,  N.Z. 

ATTLEE  (C.  M.),  19  Elvetham  Road,  Edgbaston,  Birmingham. 

BAILLIE  (Prof.  J.  B.),  King's  College,  Aberdeen. 
BAIN  (Mrs.),  50  Osborne  Place,  Aberdeen.     Hon.  Member. 
BALFOUR  (Rt.  Hon.  A.  J.),  Whittingehame,  Prestonkirk,  N.B. 
BARAL  (Prof.  S.  N.),  Gaurisankar-Saeter,  Lille  Elvedalen,  Alvdal,  Nor- 
way. 

BARKER  (H.),  Cairnmuir  Road,  Corstorphine,  Edinburgh. 
BENECKE  (E.  C.),  182  Denmark  Hill,  London,  S.E. 
BENETT  (W.),  Oatlands,  Warborough,  Wallingford. 
BERKELEY  (Capt.  H.).,  Painswick,  Gloucestershire. 
BLUNT  (H.  W.),  183  Woodstock  Road,  Oxford. 
BONAR  (J.),  1  Redington  Road,  Hampstead,  N.W. 
BOSANQUET  (Prof.  B.),  Heath  Cottage,  Oxshott,  Surrey. 
BOWMAN  (Prof.  A.  A.),  Princeton  University,  N.J.,  U.S.A. 
BRADLEY  (F.  H.),  Merton  College,  Oxford. 

BRAHAM  (Rev.  E.  G.),  c/o  Randall  &  Co.,  Newfoundland  Street,  BristoL 
BREN  (Rev.  R.),  68  Wheeleys  Road,  Edgbaston,  Birmingham. 
BRETT  (Prof.  G.  S.),  The  University,  Toronto,  Canada. 
BROAD  (Prof.  C.  D.),  The  University,  Bristol. 
BROUGH  (Prof.  J.),  Hampden  House,  London,  N.W. 

CAMERON  (Rev.  Dr.  J.  R.),  6  Albyn  Terrace,  Aberdeen. 

CARPENTER  (Rev.  Dr.  J.  E.),  11  Marston  Ferry  Road,  Oxford. 

CARR  (Prof.  H.  W.),  107  Church  St.,  Chelsea,  S.W.  3. 

CARR  (W.),  58  Elm  Park  Rd.,  Chelsea,  S.W.  3. 

CASE  (T.),  Corpus  Christi  College,  Oxford. 

CHANG  (W.  S.),  74  High  St.,  Oxford. 

CODDINGTON  (F.  J.  0.),  Training  College,  Sheffield. 

COIT  (Dr.  S.),  30  Hyde  Park  Gate,  London,  S.W. 

CONNELL  (Rev.  J.  D.),United  Free  Manse,  Nailston,  Renfrew. 

COOKE  (H.  P.),  Clevelands,  Lyndewode  Road,  Cambridge. 

COOKS  (Dr.  R.  B.),  Cornell  University,  Ithaca,  U.S.A. 

D'ARCY  (Rev.  M.  C.),  St.  Bruno's  College,  St.  Asaph,  Wales. 
DAVIDSON  (Prof.  W.  L.),  8  Queen's  Gardens,  Aberdeen. 


126  MIND   ASSOCIATION. 

DESSOULAVY  (Rev.  Dr.  C.),  Pennybridge,  Mayfield,  Sussex. 

DIXON  (Capt.  E.  T.),  Racketts,  Hythe,  Hants. 

DODD  (P.  W.),  Jesus  College,  Oxford. 

DORWARD  (A.  J.),  Queen's  University,  Belfast. 

DOUGLAS  (G.  M.),  Auchlochan,  Lesmahagow,  Lanarkshire. 

DOUGLAS  (Prof.  W.),  Rangoon  College,  Rangoon,  Burma. 

DUDDINGTON  (Mrs.  N.  A.),  13  Carlton  Terrace,  Child's  Hill,  N.W.  2. 

EDGELL  (Miss  B.),  15  Lyon  Road,  Harrow. 

EDWARD  (Rev.  Dr.  K.),  Mansefield,  Peebles. 

ELIOT  (Sir  C.  N.  E.),  K.C.M.G.,  The  British  Embassy,  Tokio,  Japan. 

ENGLISH  (Dr.  H.  B.),  Antioch  College,  Yellow  Springs,  0.,  U.S.A. 

FAWCETT  (E.  D.),  Sommerheim,  Wengen,  Switzerland. 

FIELD  (G.  C.),  The  University,  Liverpool. 

FLOWER  (Rev.  J.  C.).  Park  Street  Chapel,  Bolton. 

FORSYTE  (Prof.  T.  M.),  Grey  College,  Bloemfontein,  South  Africa. 

GALLAGHER  (Rev.  J.),  Crowton  Vicarage,  Northwich. 

GALLOWAY  (Principal  G.),  St.  Mary's  College,  St.  Andrews,  N.B. 

GEIKIE-COBB  (Rev.  Dr.  W.  F.),  40  Cathcart  Road,  S.W.  10. 

GIBSON  (Prof.  J.),  Bron  Hwfa,  Bangor,  Wales. 

GIBSON  (Prof.  W.  R.  B.),  The  University,  Melbourne,  Australia. 

GOLDSBOROUGH  (Dr.  G.  F.),  Church  Side,  Herne  Hill,  S.E. 

GORDON  (Rev.  A.  G.),  Kettle  Manse,  Fife. 

GRANGER  (Prof.  F.),  University  College,  Nottingham. 

GREIG  (J.  T.  T.),  Armstrong  College,  Newcastle-on-Tyne. 

HALDANE  (Rt.  Hon.  Viscount),  28  Queen  Anne's  Gate,  London,  S.W. 

HALLETT  (H.  F.),  The  University,  Leeds. 

HAMPTON  (Prof.  H.  V.),  Karnatak  College,  Dharwar,  Bombay,  India. 

HARDIE  (R.  P.),  13  Palmerston  Road,  Edinburgh. 

HARRIS  (C.  R.  S.),  All  Souls'  College,  Oxford. 

HARVEY  (J.  W.),  The  University,  Birmingham. 

HASAN  (S.  Z.),  New  College,  Oxford. 

HAZLITT  (Miss  V.),  50  Southwood  Lane,  Highgate,  N. 

HEADLY  (L.  C.),  House  on  the  Hill,  Woodhouse  Eaves,  Loughborough. 

HENDERSON  (C.  G.),  Bijapur,  India. 

HETHERINGTON  (Principal  H.  T.  W.),  University  College,  Exeter. 

HICKS  (Prof.  G.  D.),  9  Cranmer  Road,  Cambridge. 

HOERNLE  (Prof.  R.  F.  A.),  Armstrong  College,  Newcastle-on-Tyne. 

INGHAM  (C.  B.),  Moira  House,  Eastbourne. 

JAMES  (Rev.  J.  G.),  Flowerdale,  Potters  Road,  New  Barnet. 
JEVONS  (Dr.  F.  B.),  Bishop  Hatfield's  Hall,  Durham. 
JOACHIM  (Prof.  H.  H.),  New  College,  Oxford. 
JONES  (Miss  E.  E.  C.),  Meldon,  Weston-super-Mare. 
JONES  (Prof.  Sir  H.),  1  The  College,  Glasgow. 
JONES  (Rev.  Dr.  W.  Tudor),  14  Clifton  Park,  Bristol. 
JOSEPH  (H.  W.  B.),  New  College,  Oxford. 

KARPUR  SHRINIVASA  RAO  (Raja),  Charnarajapet,  Bangalore,  India. 

KEANE  (Rev.  H.),  Stonyhurst  College,  Blackburn. 

KEATINGE  (Dr.  M.  W.),  Tommy's  Heath,  Boar's  Hill,  Oxford. 

KEYNES  (Dr.  J.  N.),  6  Harvey  Road,  Cambridge. 

KIRKBY  (Rev.  Dr.  P.  J.),  Saham  Rectory,  Watton,  Norfolk. 

KNAPTON  (Rev.  A.  J.),  The  Vicarage,  Glee  St.  Margaret,  Craven  Arms 

Salop. 
KNOX  (Capt.  H.  V.),  3  Crick  Road,  Oxford. 

LAING  (B.  M.),  The  University,  Sheffield. 
LAIRD  (Prof.  J.),  Queen's  University,  Belfast. 
LATTA  (Prof.  R.),  4  The  College,  Glasgow. 
LAZARUS  (S.  C.),  Balliol  College,  Oxford. 
LEGQE  (A.  E.  J.),  Kingsmead,  Windsor  Forest. 


MIND   ASSOCIATION. 

LEWIS  (Dr.  E.  B.),  Glamorgan  County  Hall,  Cardiff. 
LIBRARIAN  (The),  Bedford  College,  Regent's  Park,  N.W.  1. 
LIBRARIAN  (The),  University  of  Manitoba,  Winnipeg,  Canada. 
LINDSAY  (A.  D.),  Balliol  College,  Oxford. 
LOVEDAY  (T.),  Vice-Chancellor,  The  University,  Bristol. 
LUTOSLAWSKI  (Prof.  W.),  26  Sto  Janska,  Wilno,  Poland. 

McDouGALL  (Prof.  W.),  Harvard  University,  Cambridge,  Mass.,  U.S.A. 

MCFARLANE  (Miss  M.)  50  South  wood  Lane,  Highgate.  N. 

MCINTYRE  (Dr.  J.  L.),  Abbotsville,  Cults,  Aberdeenshire. 

MclvER  (Prof.  R.  M.),  The  University,  Toronto,  Canada. 

MACKENZIE  (Prof.  J.  S.),  56  Bassett  Eoad,  North  Kensington,  W. 

MACKENZIE  (Sir  W.  L.),  4  Clarendon  Crescent,  Edinburgh. 

MACKINTOSH  (Prof.  H.  R.),  81  Colinton  Road,  Edinburgh. 

MCTAGGART  (Dr.  J.  M.  E.),  Trinity  College,  Cambridge. 

MAIR  (Prof.  A.),  26  Parkfield  Road,  Liverpool. 

MALLET  (E.  H.),  Goldney  House,  Gliftonville,  Bristol. 

MANCHESTER  (Right  Rev.  Bishop  of),  Bishop's  Court,  Manchester. 

MANNING  (W.  H.  O.),  Trinity  College,  Cambridge. 

MARETT  (Dr.  R.  R.),  Exeter  College,  Oxford. 

MARSHALL  (Mrs.  D.  H.),  Ovingdean  Hall,  Brighton. 

MARSHALL  (H.  Rutgers),  Century  Assn.,  7  West  43rd  Street,  New  York. 

MOBERLY  (Prof.  W.  H.),  The  University,  Birmingham. 

MOORE  (Dr.  G.  E.),  17  Magdalene  St.,  Cambridge. 

MORIKAWA  (Prof.  C.),  Japanische  Botschaft,  Berlin. 

MORRISON  (D.),  The  University,  St.  Andrews,  N.B. 

MORRISON  (Rev.  Dr.  W.  D.),  38  Devonshire  Place,  London,  W. 

MUIRHEAD  (Prof.  J.  H.),  The  University,  Birmingham. 

MUKERJI  (Prof.  N.  C.),  Evving  College,  Allahabad,  India. 

MURE  (G.  R.  G.),  Merton  College,  Oxford. 

MURRAY  (J.),  Christ  Church,  Oxford. 

NAIRNE  (A.),  Jesus  College,  Cambridge. 

Nic6LLS  (B.  E.),  White  House,  Sandeistead  Village,  Surrey. 

NUNN  (Dr.  T.  P.),  Day  Training  College,  Southampton  Row,  W.C. 

OAKELEY  (Miss  H.  D.),  Passmore  Edwards  Settlement,  Tavistock  Place, 

W.C. 

O'NEILL  (E.  E.),  26  Cromwell  Road,  Belfast. 
OSGOOD  (G.  L.),  Manor  House,  Petersham,  Surrey. 

PARKINSON  (Rev.  Dr.  H.),  Oscott  College,  Birmingham. 
PATON  (H.  J.),  Queen's  College,  Oxford. 
PICKARD-CAMBRIDGE  (W.  A.),  Worcester  College,  Oxford. 
POLLOCK  (Sir  F.,  Bart.),  21  Hyde  Park  Place,  London,  W. 
PRICHARD  (H.  A.),  Trinity  College,  Oxford. 
PRINGLE-PATTISON  (Prof.  A.  S.),  The  Haining,  Selkirk,  N.B. 

QUICK  (Rev.  0.  C.),  25  Sanderson  Road,  Jesmond,  Newcastle-on-Tyne. 

RAHDER  (J.),  12  Colignyplein,  The  Hague,  Holland. 

RAMANATHAN  (Rao  Bahadur  K.  B.),  16  Venkatachala  St.,  Triplicane,  India. 

RANADE  (Prof.  R.  D.),  Fergusson  College,  Poona,  India. 

RASHDALL  (Very  Rev.  Dr.  H.),  The  Deanery,  Carlisle. 

READ  (Prof.  C.),  University  College,  W.C. 

RELTON  (Rev.  Dr.  H.  M.),  The  Vicarage,  Isle  worth,  Middlesex. 

RIVBTT  (Miss  D.  M.),  Bedford  College,  Regent's  Park,  N.W.  1. 

ROBINSON  (Prof.  A.),  Observatory  House,  Durham. 

ROGERS  (R.  A.  P.),  Trinity  College,  Dublin. 

Ross  (Prof.  G.  R.  T.),  Government  College,  Rangoon,  Burma. 

Ross  (W.  D.),  Oriel  College,  Oxford. 

ROTH  (H.  L.),  Exeter  College,  Oxford. 

ROWLANDS  (Prof.  W.  S.),  Robertson  College,  Jubbulpore,  India. 

RUSSELL  (Hon.  B.),  Trinity  College,  Cambridge. 

RUBSELL  (L.  J.),  Brousterland,  East  Kilbride,  Lanarkshire,  N.B. 


128  MIND   ASSOCIATION. 

SCHILLER  (Dr.  F.  C.  S.),  Corpus  Christ!  College,  Oxford. 

SCOTT  (Miss  E.  S.),  Education  Department,  The  University,  Birmingham. 

SCOTT  (Prof.  J.  W.),  University  College,  Cardiff. 

SETH  (Prof.  J.),  20  Braid  Avenue,  Edinburgh. 

SHAND  (A.  F.),  1  Edwardes  Place,  London,  W. 

SHEARMAN  (Dr.  A.  T.),  University  College,  London,  W.C. 

SHELTON  (F.  D.),  Rosedale,  Alberta,  Canada. 

SHELTON  (H.  S.),  151  Richmond  Road,  Twickenham. 

SIDDHANTA  (A.  K.),  33  Amherst  St.,  Calcutta. 

SIDQWICK  (A.),  Trewoofe  Orchard,  St.  Buryan,  Cornwall. 

SIDGWICK  (Mrs.  H.),  Fisher's  Hill,  Woking,  Surrey.     Hon.  Member. 

SMITH  (A.  H.),  New  College,  Oxford. 

SMITH  (Prof.  J.  A.),  Magdalen  College,  Oxford. 

SMITH  (Prof.  N.  Kemp),  The  University,  Edinburgh. 

SORLEY  (Prof.  W.  R.),  St.  Giles',  Chesterton  Lane,  Cambridge. 

STEBBING  (Miss  L.  S.),  27  Belsize  Park,  N.W.  3. 

STEWART  (Prof.  J.  A.),  14  Bradmore  Road,  Oxford. 

STOCKS  (J.  L.),  St.  John's  College,  Oxford. 

STOKES  (Prof.  G.  J.),  Queen's  College,  Cork. 

STOUT  (Prof.  G.  F.),  Craigard,  St.  Andrews,  N.B.     Hon.  Member. 

STRONG  (Prof.  C.  A.),  c/o  Credit  Lyonnais,  19  Boulevard  des  Italiensr 

Paris. 

STURT  (H.),  5  Park  Terrace,  Oxford.     Hon.  Member. 
SUTCLIFFE  (J.  W.),  14  Clifton  Road,  Halifax,  Yorks. 

TITCHENER  (Prof.  E.  B.),  Cornell  University,  Ithaca,  N.Y.,  U.S.A.     Hon. 

Member. 
TOLANI  (M.  N.),  Fitzwilliam  Hall,  Cambridge. 

UNDERBILL  (G.  E.),  10  Northmoor  Road,  Oxford. 

WALKER  (J.),  Wooldale,  Thongsbridge,  Huddersfield. 

WALKER  (Rev.  L.  J.  K.,  S.J.),  Campion  Hall,  Oxford. 

WALLEY  (J.  T.),  Chardleigh  Green,  Chard,  Somerset. 

WARD  (Prof.  J.),  6  Selwyn  Gardens,  Cambridge. 

WARREN  (Mrs.  Fiske),  8  Mount  Vernon  Place,  Boston,  U.S.A. 

WATERLOW  (S.  P.),  3  Temple  Gardens,  London,  E.G. 

WEBB  (Prof.  C.  C.  J.),  Holy  well  Ford,  Oxford. 

WIDGERY  (Prof.  A.  G.),  The  College,  Baroda,  India. 

WHITCOMB  (P.  W.),  Shawnee,  Osborne  Road,  Walton-on-Thames. 

WHITEHEAD  (Rev.  L.  G.),  Selwyn  College,  Dunedin,  N.Z. 

WILLIAMSON  (C.  C.  H.),  7  Park  Mansions,  South  Lambeth  Road,  S.W.  8. 

WILSON  (S.  F.),  2  Sherwood  Street,  Warsop,  Mansfield,  Notts. 

WOODS  (Miss  A.),  St.  Ives,  Cross  Path,  Radlett,  Herts. 


Those  who  wish  to  join  the  Association  should  communicate 
with  the  Hon.  Secretary,  Mr.  G.  R.  G.  MURE,  Merton  College, 
Oxford ;  or  with  the  Hon.  Treasurer,  Dr.  F.  C.  S.  SCHILLER, 
Corpus  Christi  College,  Oxford,  to  whom  the  yearly  subscrip- 
tion of  sixteen  shillings  should  be  paid.  In  return  for  this 
subscription  members  receive  MIND  gratis  and  post  free,  and 
are  entitled  to  buy  back-numbers  both  of  the  Old  and  the 
New  Series  at  half  price.  Members  resident  in  America  can 
pay  their  subscription  ($4)  into  the  account  of  the  Hon. 
Treasurer  (Dr.  F.  C.  S.  Schiller)  at  the  Fifth  Avenue  Bank, 
44th  Street,  New  York. 


VOL.  xxxi.     No.   122.]  [APRIL,   1922. 


MIND 


A  QUARTERLY   REVIEW 

OF 

PSYCHOLOGY  AND  PHILOSOPHY 


I.— THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ACCOMPANIMENTS 
OF  INSTINCTIVE  ACTION. 

BY  G.  C.  FIELD. 

IN  a  previous  article  on  this  subject  I  attempted  to  make 
some  suggestions  about  the  proper  method  of  approach  to  the 
problems  of  Instinct  and  instinctive  action.  And  in  the 
course  of  that  article  I  referred  to  the  views  of  those  who 
hold  that  every  kind  of  activity  which  we  can  call  instinctive 
is  necessarily  accompanied  by  some  kind  or  another  of 
conscious  experience,  and  that  one  way,  perhaps  for  the 
psychologist  the  only  way,  of  defining  instinctive  behaviour 
is  to  state  the  particular  form  of  conscious  experience  by 
which  it  is  accompanied.  I  propose  now  to  attempt  an 
examination  of  this  point  of  view,  and  to  ask  whether  every 
kind  of  instinctive  behaviour  is  necessarily  accompanied  by 
some  one  kind  of  conscious  experience,  and  if  so,  by  what 
kind. 

At  the  outset  we  must  distinguish  between  two  different 
questions.  It  is  one  thing  to  ask  whether  all  instinctive  be- 
haviour, in  particular,  instinctive  bodily  action,  is  necessarily 
accompanied  by  one  kind  of  conscious  mental  process,  and 
quite  another  to  ask  whether  certain  kinds  of  conscious 
mental  process  should  be  properly  described  as  instinctive  in 
the  same  sense  as  certain  instinctive  bodily  actions,  even 
though  the  two  forms  of  activity,  the  conscious  mental  pro- 
cesses and  the  bodily  actions,  are  not  always  or  necessarily 
found  together.  Our  opinion  on  the  latter  point  will  largely 
depend  on  how  much  we  include  in  our  definition  of  Instinct 
and  instinctive.  If,  for  instance,  anything  that  proceeds 

9 


130  G.  c.  FIELD: 

from  our  innate  psycho-physical  structure  is  to  be  called  in- 
stinctive, we  shall  probably  not  have  much  difficulty  in  apply- 
ing the  term  at  any  rate  to  many  of  our  conscious  mental 
processes.  If  we  mean  more  than  that  by  the  use  of  the 
term  '  instinctive/  it  will  be  a  matter  for  investigation  in  each 
particular  case  whether  the  conscious  mental  process  in 
question  resembles  the  instinctive  action  to  such  an  extent 
that  we  are  warranted  in  applying  the  same  term  '  instinctive ' 
to  both  of  them.  Some  of  the  precautions  suggested  in  my 
last  article  might  possibly  be  found  to  bear  on  this  investiga- 
tion. But  in  any  case,  that  is  not  the  question  which  is 
being  discussed  in  the  present  paper,  which  deals  only  with 
the  former  question.  What,  if  any,  are  the  conscious  mental 
processes  which  always  and  necessarily  accompany  instinctive 
behaviour  ? 

It  seems  to  me  that  any  discussion  of  Instinct  must  start 
from  an  examination  of  instinctive  bodily  action,  because  it 
is  to  this  kind  of  behaviour  that  the  term  '  instinctive  '  is 
universally  and  unquestioningly  recognised  to  apply.  And 
no  definition  of  the  term  could  possibly  be  accepted  unless  it 
could  be  applied  to  the  bodily  actions  which  are  admitted  by 
everyone  to  be  properly  called  instinctive.  But  before  we 
ask  what  are  the  conscious  accompaniments  of  this  kind  of 
action,  there  is  one  other  preliminary  consideration  that  we 
must  bear  in  mind.  We,  like  many  at  any  rate  of  the  other 
animals,  are  conscious  beings.  And  therefore  any  kind  of 
action,  instinctive  or  otherwise,  taken  while  we  are  conscious 
must  have  some  kind  of  conscious  accompaniment.  But 
that  would  not  warrant  us  in  putting  the  conscious  accompani- 
ment that  we  found  in  any  particular  case  of  instinctive  action 
into  the  definition  of  "  instinctive,"  unless  we  had  reason  to 
believe  that  there  was  some  necessary  connexion  between  the 
action  and  the  conscious  accompaniment,  so  that  we  could 
not  have  one  without  the  other.  It  is  possible  that,  in  our- 
selves for  instance,  instinctive  action  might  be  accompanied 
by  some  form  of  consciousness  without  being  necessarily  con- 
nected with,  still  less  conditioned  or  affected  by  this  conscious- 
ness. In  such  a  case  it  would  be  clearly  wrong  to  give  the 
conscious  accompaniment  in  our  definition  of  instinctive 
action. 

One  more  principle  of  method  may  be  suggested.  It  seems 
likely  that  a  good  deal  of  the  difficulties  and  differences  of 
opinion  upon  the  subject  arise  because  investigators  have 
started  the  consideration  of  it  from  a  complicated  particular 
instance  or  a  border-line  case,  where  instinct  was  clearly 
mixed  up  with  a  good  deal  else  or  where  it  was  uncertain 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  ACCOMPANIMENTS  OF  INSTINCTIVE  ACTION.  131 

whether  the  behaviour  in  question  should  properly  be  called 
instinctive  or  not.  As  a  general  rule  it  seems  preferable,  if 
we  are  to  start  with  an  investigation  of  a  particular  instance 
at  all,  to  start  with  an  instance  which  unquestionably  belongs 
tg  the  class  of  things  which  we  are  discussing,  and  where 
there  is  as  little  as  possible  of  any  other  element.  Then  in 
the  light  of  what  we  have  learned  from  that  we  may  consider 
the  border-line  cases.  Thus  in  the  case  of  Instinct  it  seems 
to  me  advisable  to  start,  not  from  the  behaviour  of  man  and 
the  difficult  question  exactly  how  much  of  this  behaviour  we 
can  call  instinctive  and  how  much  is  due  to  other  factors,  nor 
even  from  moorhens  diving  and  a  discussion  of  the  exact 
point  of  time  at  which  their  behaviour  becomes  modified  by 
experience,  but  rather  from  certain  actions  of  insects  where 
we  seem  to  get  as  close  as  possible  to  purely  instinctive 
action. 

Take  any  typical  instances  of  insect  behaviour.  We  find 
a  series  of  actions,  often  very  complicated,  performed  with 
extreme  precision,  and  the  whole  admirably  adapted  to  fulfil 
a  certain  purpose,  the  preservation  of  the  insect  itself  or  the 
preservation  of  its  offspring.  The  Ammophila  wasp  seizes  a 
caterpillar,  stings  it  in  the  exact  places  where  the  sting  will 
paralyse  it  without  killing  it,  places  it  at  the  end  of  the 
burrow  it  has  dug,  lays  an  egg  on  it,  and  then  seals  up  the 
end  of  the  burrow.1  Thus  it  secures  that  the  larva  will  be 
hatched  out  of  the  egg  in  safety,  and  will  have  the  supply  of 
fresh  meat  which  is  needful  for  it  to  grow  to  maturity.  Here 
is  an  action  which,  if  performed  by  a  human  being,  could  only 
be  explained  by  a  great  amount  of  acquired  knowledge  and 
skill,  a  clear  foresight  of  the  end  to  be  attained,  and  an  under- 
standing of  the  exact  means  necessary  to  attain  it.  But  we 
know  that  the  insect  cannot  have  learnt  or  acquired  this 
knowledge,  and  cannot  have  any  foresight  of  the  result  which 
it  never  sees  or  has  seen.  We  may  say  further  that  it  shows 
no  interest  in  the  result.  And  it  is  clear,  also,  if  we  consider 
experiments  like  those  of  Fabre  and  Captain  K.  W.  G. 
Kingston,  described  in  his  fascinating  book,  A  Naturalist  in 
Himalaya,  that  there  is  no  understanding  of  the  situation 
and  of  what  is  happening,  and  no  capacity  for  analysing  and 
distinguishing  the  elements  of  the  situation  or  for  modifying 
the  action  to  suit  changes  artificially  produced. 

Thus  the  Ammophila,  if  her  burrow  is  broken  open  while 
she  is  collecting  material  to  seal  it  up,  and  the  caterpillar  and 

1 1  am  aware  that  the  experiments  of  the  Peckhams  threw  some  doubt 
on  the  alleged  infallible  skill  of  the  operation.  But  the  exact  degree  of 
accuracy  displayed  by  the  wasp  is  immaterial  to  the  present  argument. 


132  G.  c.  FIELD: 

egg  extracted  and  laid  outside  the  door,  will  make  no  effort 
to  repair  the  burrow  nor  to  replace  the  caterpillar  and  the 
egg  which  are  lying  in  full  view,  but  will  calmly  proceed  to 
seal  up  the  burrow  as  if  nothing  had  happened.  The  Mason 
Bee  builds  cells  of  mortar  and  fills  them  with  honey.  If  the 
cells  are  broken  down  before  they  are  completed  she  builds 
them  up  again.  But  once  they  are  completed  she  must  go 
on  to  put  the  honey  in,  and  if  they  are  broken  down  after 
this,  she  makes  no  effort  to  repair  them,  but  goes  on  putting 
the  honey  in,  cheerfully  oblivious  of  the  fact  that  it  is  all 
running  out  again  before  her  eyes.  The  spider  builds  her 
wonderful  web  in  a  certain  order  ;  and  if  the  work  she  has 
already  done  is  cut  or  broken,  she  does  not  turn  back  to  re- 
pair it,  though  she  has  all  the  resources  necessary  for  that 
purpose,  but  goes  on  in  the  fixed  order,  irrespective  of  the 
fact  that  the  web  is  getting  into  a  worse  and  wTorse  tangle  all 
the  time,  so  that  it  would  be  almost  useless  for  her  purposes. 

It  is  clear  from  these  and  many  other  instances,  both  from 
the  character  of  the  action  and  from  the  conditions  under 
which  it  takes  place,  that  these  actions  of  insects  are  certainly 
not  caused  or  accompanied  by  anything  remotely  like  the 
state  of  mind  from  which  a  similar  action  would  proceed  in 
the  case  of  a  human  being.  But  from  what  state  of  mind 
do  they  proceed  ?  What  conscious  experience  necessarily  ac- 
companies instinctive  action  ?  Let  us  consider  the  possi- 
bilities. 

(1)  There  may  be  the  consciousness  of  movement,  the 
feeling  in  the  muscles  or  the  rest  of  the  body  when  any  part 
of  the  body  moves  or  is  moved.  This  consciousness  must  be 
thought  of  rather  as  the  result  of  the  movement  than  as  its 
cause  :  it  does  not,  by  itself,  affect  or  modify  the  movement 
in  any  way.  To  describe  it  in  terms  of  our  own  experience, 
we  should  say  that  we  feel  the  body  moving  without  being 
able  to  control  or  check  the  movement ;  as  when  we  blink 
our  eyes  in  response  to  a  sudden  and  unexpected  feint  of  a 
blow.  ('2)  There  may  be  foresight  and  desire  not  of  the 
ultimate  result  but  of  each  particular  movement.  We  can 
find  this,  too,  in  our  own  experience.  We  may  want  to  get 
up  and  stretch  ourselves  ;  we  may,  if  we  are  young  and  active 
enough,  want  to  jump  or  run,  not  with  any  thought  of  any 
results  that  may  be  produced,  but  simply,  as  we  say,  for  the 
mere  pleasure  of  jumping  and  running.  This  may  be  desire 
in  the  full  sense,  involving  a  previous  idea  of  the  movement 
and  a  desire  to  realise  that  idea.  Perhaps,  therefore,  the 
Mason  Bee  desires  to  go  through  in  this  order  each  of  the 
particular  actions  involved  in  building  her  cells  and  filling 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  ACCOMPANIMENTS  OF  INSTINCTIVE  ACTION.  133 

them  with  honey,  though  she  may  have  no  desire  at  all  that 
the  cells  should  be  built  and  filled  with  honey.  (3)  Mr. 
Shand  says  that  the  invariable  conscious  accompaniment  of 
instinctive  action  is  '  a  feeling  of  impulse.'  I  confess  to 
finding  this  phrase  ambiguous.  It  may  be  applied  to  either 
of  the  two  previous  experiences.  But  I  cannot  find  in  my 
own  experience  a  third  thing,  different  in  kind  from  either 
of  these  two,  to  which  the  name  could  be  properly  applied. 
(4)  It  might  be,  as  Dr.  McDougall  suggests,  that  instinctive 
action  is  always  accompanied  by  an  emotion,  each  kind  of 
action  being  bound  up  with  a  particular  emotion.  (5)  Finally, 
there  is  Dr.  James  Drever's  suggestion  that  instinctive  action 
is  invariably  accompanied  by  a  feeling  of  interest.  But  this 
phrase  by  itself  is  obscure,  and  may  mean  several  different 
things.  It  might,  for  instance,  refer  to  an  interest  in  the 
external  stimulus,  the  situation  or  that  factor  in  the  situation 
which  is  the  occasion  of  the  instinctive  action.  Thus  it  might 
be  argued  that,  if  the  sight  of  a  caterpillar  stimulates  the 
wasp  to  seize  it  and  sting  it  in  a  particular  way,  the  wasp 
must  have  had  a  feeling  of  interest  in  the  caterpillar  to  make 
her  notice  it  in  all  its  surroundings.  This  would  be  a  pre- 
liminary feeling  of  interest,  necessary  to  set  the  action  going. 
But  that  is  quite  a  different  thing  from  an  interest  in  either 
(a)  an  idea  of  the  movements,  which  is  in  consciousness  be- 
fore the  movements  take  place,  (6)  the  results,  immediate 
or  remote,  produced  by  the  movement,  or  (c)  the  actual 
movements  themselves,  while  they  are  going  on.  And  there 
is  a  further  distinction  to  be  borne  in  mind.  If  we  say  that 
there  is  a  feeling  of  interest  in  the  movements  themselves, 
that  is  by  no  means  the  same  thing  as  saying  that  the  feeling 
of  interest  causes  or  determines  the  movements.  We  can 
see  the  difference  in  our  own  experience  of  reflex  action.  If 
a  doctor  tests  our  reflexes,  we  may  be  very  keenly  interested 
in  the  movements  that  we  make,  but  it  is  obvious  that  we 
cannot  say  in  any  sense  that  our  interest  determines  or  causes 
the  knee-jerks,  which  would  occur  just  the  same  whether  we 
were  interested  or  not.  So  that  a  '  feeling  of  interest '  may 
mean  several  different  things,  any  one  of  which  may  be 
present  without  the  others. 

Perhaps  as  a  representative  instance  of  the  views  which 
assign  the  maximum  amount  of  conscious  accompaniment  to 
instinctive  action  we  may  take  the  account  given  by  Prof. 
Stout  in  the  last  edition  of  his  Manual  of  Psychology.  Any 
statement  from  such  a  source  comes  to  us  with  particular 
weight  and  authority,  and  we  are  not  likely  to  find  an  abler 
statement  of  the  views  in  question  anywhere  else.  It  may, 


134  G.   C.   FIELD: 

therefore,  be  worth  while  to  give  a  somewhat  detailed  ex- 
amination of  the  account  there  put  forward.  It  is  to  be  found 
in  Book  III.,  Chapter  I.  of  the  third  edition  of  the  Manual,  and 
more  especially  in  various  passages  on  pages  343-357. 

Prof.  Stout  is  concerned  to  distinguish  instinctive  action 
sharply  and  definitely  from  reflex  action,  with  which  it  is  so 
often  identified.  '  Reflex  action,'  he  writes  (p.  343),  'is  of  a 
nature  fundamentally  different  from  instinctive  conduct.  The 
difference  is  that  instinctive  conduct  does  and  reflex  action 
does  not  presuppose  the  co-operation  of  intelligent  conscious- 
ness, including  under  this  head  interest,  attention,  variation 
of  behaviour  according  as  its  results  are  satisfactory  or  un- 
satisfactory, and  the  power  of  learning  by  experience.'  This 
is  clearly  not  a  mere  arbitrary  statement  of  the  kind  of 
behaviour  to  which  he  proposes  to  apply  the  term  '  instinctive,' 
for  he  asserts  the  presence  of  these  elements  in  action  to 
which  the  term  '  instinctive '  would  be  applied  by  universal 
agreement,  including  instances  of  the  behaviour  of  insects 
such  as  those  described  above. 

The  first  difficulty  that  I  find  in  this  account  lies  in  the 
distinction  on  which  it  is  based  between  instinctive  and  re- 
flex action.  A  good  deal  of  the  argument  seems  to  me  to  be 
vitiated  by  being  based  on  a  comparison  between  an  experi- 
ence of  reflex  action  in  ourselves  and  instinctive  action  as 
shown,  say,  in  insects.  Because  reflex  action  in  ourselves 
is  comparatively  simple  and  limited,  Prof.  Stout  seems  to 
argue  that  the  behaviour  of  insects,  which  does  not  display 
this  simplicity  and  these  limitations,  must  therefore  be  ac- 
companied by  conscious  and  intelligent  processes  which  are 
not  present  in  the  case  of  reflex  action.  But  that  is  surely 
to  beg  the  question.  For  the  point  at  issue  is  just  this, 
whether  it  is  not  possible  for  reflex  action,  as  we  know  it,  to 
be  developed  in  other  species  to  a  very  much  higher  pitch  of 
complication  and  elaboration. 

Further,  a  good  many  of  Prof.  Stout's  arguments  about 
instinctive  action  would,  it  seems  to  me,  apply  with  equal 
force  to  reflex  action.  In  our  own  case  reflex  actions,  of 
course,  may  be  accompanied  by  a  considerable  amount  of  in- 
telligent consciousness.  And,  owing  to  the  presence  of  this 
intelligent  consciousness  in  us,  we  may  sometimes  to  some 
degree  check,  control  or  modify  the  reflex  action.  Thus  we 
may  suppress  or  partially  suppress  a  sneeze  or  the  blinking 
of  our  eyes  at  the  feint  of  a  blow.  We  say  that  the  re- 
sultant action  in  such  a  case  is  not  entirely  reflex,  but  that 
part  of  it  is  intelligently  controlled,  thus  still  retaining  the 
sharp  distinction  between  what  is  due  to  the  reflex  and  what 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  ACCOMPANIMENTS  OF  INSTINCTIVE  ACTION.  135 

is  due  to  intelligence.  But  why  should  we  not  speak  in 
the  same  way  of  instinctive  action  ?  The  question  is  not 
whether  animals  which  act  instinctively  may  or  may  not 
sometimes  modify  their  behaviour  under  the  influence  of  in- 
telligence. It  is  rather  whether  instinctive  action  is  neces- 
sarily bound  up  with  and  determined  by  intelligence,  whether 
it  is  from  the  beginning,  as  Prof.  Stout  says  (p.  357),  '  essen- 
tially conditioned  by  intelligent  consciousness  '.  Prof.  Stout's 
argument  that  subsequent  modifications  of  behaviour  by  in- 
telligence prove  that  the  behaviour  must  have  been  deter- 
mined by  conscious  intelligence  from  the  beginning,  would 
surely,  then,  apply  with  equal  force  to  reflex  action.  For 
that  also,  as  in  the  case  of  the  suppressed  sneeze,  may  be 
modified  by  intelligence.  And,  so  far  as  it  is  based  on  such 
considerations,  the  distinction  between  instinctive  and  reflex 
action  seems  to  fall  to  the  ground.  And  there  seems  so  far 
no  reason  why  we  should  not  say  of  instinctive  action,  as  we 
do  of  reflex  action,  that  it  is  qua  instinctive  essentially 
different  from  and  undetermined  by  intelligence,  though  in 
any  particular  case  the  behaviour,  which  would  otherwise  be 
purely  instinctive,  might  be  modified  by  intelligence. 

But  we  must  examine  further  the  case  for  the  influence  of 
intelligence  in  behaviour  which  is  usually  regarded  as  in- 
stinctive. I  may  be  unduly  sceptical,  but  I  confess  that  I  am 
still  not  perfectly  convinced  by  any  of  the  evidence  I  have 
yet  seen  for  the  actual  occurrence  of  intelligent  action  in 
insect  behaviour.  The  great  difficulty,  I  suppose,  in  assum- 
ing its  presence  is  that,  if  it  is  there,  its  action  seems  extra- 
ordinarily fitful  and  erratic.  Some  of  the  very  few  alleged 
cases,  if  due  to  intelligence  at  all,  seem  to  argue  a  relatively 
high  development  of  that  faculty.  And  yet  in  other  cases 
which  do  not  seem  to  call  for  any  greater  exercise  of  it,  the 
same  insect  will  fail  so  conspicuously  to  show  the  slightest 
signs  of  its  presence.  Of  course,  the  same  thing  may  strike 
us  at  first  sight  in  the  behaviour  of  certain  human  beings. 
But  in  such  cases  a  very  little  inspection  will  probably  show 
us  some  ground  or  principle  of  these  limitations  in  the  appli- 
cation of  intelligence.  But  it  is  difficult  to  find  any  such  in- 
telligible principle  in  these  instances  of  insect  behaviour. 

But  apart  from  that  the  instances  themselves  seem  to  lack 
decisiveness.  A  good  many  of  those  which  are  commonly 
quoted  do  not  seem  to  necessitate  an  ascription  of  them  to 
intelligence  at  all.  When  a  physical  hindrance  to  the  per- 
formance of  the  actual  movements  calls  forth  a  response 
which  did  not  show  itself  when  the  movement  was  un- 
hindered, it  seems  just  as  natural  to  say  that  a  difference  in 


136  G.  c.  FIELD: 

the  stimulus  produced  a  different  reaction  as  to  suppose  an 
intelligent  appreciation  of  the  situation.  There  is  no  diffi- 
culty that  I  can  see  in  supposing  some  such  kind  of  alterna- 
tive mechanism  in  the  animal's  structure  which  could  vary 
the  action  in  response  to  a  perceptible  difference  in  the  sur- 
rounding circumstances.  Such  a  case  would  be  that  of  Dr. 
Peckham's  wasps  who  tried  to  drag  into  the  burrow  spiders 
which  were  too  large  and  stuck  in  the  entrance  or  half-way 
down,  whereupon  they  brought  the  spider  out  and  enlarged 
the  burrow  before  taking  it  in  again.  The  single  instance 
which  he  reported  where  a  wasp  on  one  occasion  enlarged 
the  burrow  before  finding  that  the  spider  stuck  in  it  is  on  a 
different  footing.  There,  certainly,  the  most  natural  explana- 
tion of  the  action  would  be  an  intelligent  appreciation  of  the 
situation.  But  such  a  case  is  almost  unique.  And  there  is 
this  to  be  noted  about  it  and  the  one  or  two  other  cases  which 
stand  on  the  same  footing.  So  far  as  I  know,  they  are  all 
isolated  cases  observed  under  natural  conditions.  I  do  not 
think  that  any  such  cases  were  found  under  experimentally 
controlled  conditions,  which  seem  to  have  given  uniformly 
negative  results.  That,  at  any  rate,  is  Fabre's  conclusion. 

In  spite  of  these  considerations,  I  would  not  demand  of 
others  that  they  share  my  scepticism.  It  may  possibly  be  a 
personal  reaction  against  an  earlier  tendency  to  anthropo- 
morphise  unduly  the  behaviour  of  animals.  And  it  is  cer- 
tainly not  in  any  way  essential  to  my  argument  to  maintain 
that  insects  never  show  any  intelligent  modification  of 
behaviour.  But  I  do  maintain  that  a  great  deal,  if  not  most 
of  their  behaviour  shows  no  signs  of  intelligence  at  all,  and 
is,*  indeed,  such  that  it  is  very  difficult  to  suppose  its  presence 
or  its  influence. 

We  have  not  yet  come  face  to  face  with  the  question, 
What  do  we  mean  by  this  intelligent  consciousness  about 
which  we  are  arguing  ?  How  much  do  we  include  in  it  ? 
Prof.  Stout  answers  (p.  354)  that  the  minimum  that  we 
must  include  in  it  is,  '  (1)  attention  selective  and  prospective, 
making  possible  the  guidance  of  motor  activity  by  complex 
and  variable  groups  of  sensory  data ;  (2)  appreciation  of  re- 
lative success  and  failure,  making  possible  persistency  with 
varied  effort.'  Let  us  consider  these  points. 

(1)  Is  all  attention  necessarily  intelligent?  It  seems  to 
me  difficult  to  apply  the  term  to  cases,  for  instance,  of  in- 
voluntary attention  aroused  by  the  intensity  of  the  stimulus, 
such  as  a  sudden  bright  light  or  loud  explosion,  or  to  the 
attention  that  we  give  to  the  stimulus  of  a  reflex  action,  such 
as  the  blow  aimed  at  our  face  which  makes  us  flinch  and 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  ACCOMPANIMENTS  OF  INSTINCTIVE  ACTION.  137 

blink  our  eyes.  Strictly  speaking,  I  should  have  thought 
that  intelligence  could  only  be  asserted  of  attention  which  is 
due  to  some  previous  process  of  thought,  and  that  it  involved 
some  kind  of  knowledge  of  what  it  was  that  we  were  looking 
for.  But  this  is  clearly  not  the  case  with  the  wasp  who 
attends  to  the  caterpillar  the  first  time  that  she  catches  one 
as  intensely  as  the  last.  I  do  not  see  any  evidence  that  there 
is  anything  resembling  our  voluntary  and  conscious  selective 
attention.  The  wasp  does  not  know  what  she  is  looking  for, 
and  we  do  not  even  know  that  she  is  conscious  of  looking  for 
anything.  She  may  just  as  well  feel  simply  impelled  to  fly 
about  until  a  caterpillar  crosses  her  field  of  vision,  when  the 
impulse  to  further  action  follows  at  once. 

And  what  is  her  awareness  of  the  caterpillar  like  ?  What 
does  it  mean  to  her  ?  It  seems  to  me  that  the  caterpillar 
means  to  the  wasp  simply  a  certain  action  with  regard  to  it 
and  nothing  more.  It  certainly  cannot  mean  food  for  her 
offspring.  Andlt  seems  equally  evident  that  it  does  not  even 
mean  a  well-stocked  burrow  with  an  egg  on  the  top,  or  she 
would  not  regard  both  caterpillar  and  egg  with  such  complete 
indifference  as  she  did  in  Captain  Hingston's  experiment, 
when  the  burrow  was  broken  open  and  the  caterpillar  and 
egg  laid  in  full  view  outside  the  entrance.  And,  as  this  and 
similar  experiments  show,  the  caterpillar  only  means  this 
action  to  her  at  a  certain  stage  in  the  whole  instinctive  pro- 
cess. At  other  stages  it  seems  to  mean  nothing  at  all  to  her. 
As  Fabre  repeatedly  points  out,  there  seems  no  capacity  in 
insects  for  going  back  over  any  stage  in  a  process  once  com- 
pleted and  repairing  damage  or  doing  over  again  what  has 
once  been  done.  So  that  it  seems  natural  to  say  that  the 
action  is  not  determined  by  the  consciousness  of  the  object 
but  rather  that  it  determines  the  consciousness,  if  indeed 
there  is  anything  that  we  could  call  consciousness  at  all.  For 
if  the  object  simply  means  a  certain  action  to  the  wasp  and 
nothing  more,  I  should  even  question  whether  we  can  properly 
speak  of  a  conscious  awareness  of  it  at  all.  I  would  rather 
say  that  the  attention  is  part  of  the  action,  and  as  such  con- 
ditioned by  the  innate  structure  of  the  animal  just  as  the  rest 
of  the  action  is,  not  that  the  attention  causes  or  conditions 
the  action. 

(2)  But  it  is  the  second  of  Prof.  Stout's  conditions  which 
is  the  real  crux  of  the  question,  the  appreciation  of  relative 
success  and  failure,  and  the  consequent  power  of  varying 
effort.  A  good  deal  here  obviously  depends  on  the  degree  of 
qualification  implied  by  the  term  '  relative  '.  It  might  so  cut 
down  the  meaning  of  success  and  failure  as  to  leave  nothing 


138  G.  c.  FIELD: 

but  the  consciousness  of  whether  the  action  was  proceeding 
smoothly  unhindered  by  immediate  physical  obstruction.  It 
is  natural  to  believe  that  there  is  this  amount  of  consciousness, 
though  it  would  obviously  be  impossible  either  to  prove  or 
disprove  it.  But  that  by  itself  would  hardly  amount  to  in- 
telligence. And  Prof.  Stout  clearly  means  more  than  that. 
For  he  speaks  (p.  351)  of  the  animals  being  '  continuously 
interested  in  the  development  of  what  is  for  them  one  and 
the  same  situation  or  course  of  events,'  and  of  their  '  trying 
again  when  a  certain  perceptible  result  is  not  attained'. 

If  this  were  indisputably  shown  to  be  present,  it  might  or 
might  not  be  a  proof  of  intelligence.  But  it  seems  to  me 
that  these  are  just  the  features  which  the  behaviour  of  insects 
under  experimental  conditions  does  not  show.  I  should  have 
thought  that  a  '  continuous  interest  in  the  development  of 
the  situation '  involved  at  the  very  least  a  realisation  of  the 
connexion  between  the  different  stages  in  the  process,  and  an 
interest  in  the  preservation  of  the  perceptible  results  already 
attained.  But  it  is  difficult  to  claim  this  either  for  Captain 
Kingston's  wasp,  or  for  Fabre's  Mason  Bees,  who  went  on 
filling  their  cells  with  honey  after  they  had  been  visibly 
broken  open.  It  might  be  said  that  the  Mason  Bees  showed 
an  interest  in  the  process  of  building  their  cell  until  that  task 
was  completed,  and  then  transferred  this  interest  to  the  filling 
of  them  with  honey.  But  what  sort  of '  interest '  can  this  be 
which  is  thus  divided  up  into  absolutely  water-tight  compart- 
ments, so  that  it  can  suddenly  stop  short  at  one  point  in  a 
continuous  process  and,  as  it  were,  start  afresh  ?  For  the 
process  is  obviously  continuous  and  the  latter  stages  are 
closely  connected  with  the  former.  I  find  it  difficult  to  believe 
in  this  continuous  interest,  and  impossible  to  believe  that 
there  is  any  intelligent  appreciation  of  the  process  as  a  whole. 
As  for  the  '  perceptible  result,'  surely  a  spider's  web  would 
afford  an  illustration  and  a  test  case  of  this,  if  anything  did. 
And  yet  in  Captain  Kingston's  experiment,  already  referred 
to,  the  perceptible  result  was  conspicuously  not  attained,  and 
yet  the  spider  seemed  quite  undisturbed  by  this.  She  only 
altered  her  behaviour  when  the  cutting  of  the  web  went  so 
far  that  her  freedom  of  movement  in  the  path  marked  out 
by  her  routine  was  checked.  And  this  seems  the  character- 
istic of  nearly  all  the  reported  cases  of  modification  of  be- 
haviour :  it  only  occurs  when  the  actual  physical  movement 
is  interfered  with.  And  this  makes  it  difficult  to  believe  that 
in  ordinary  insect  behaviour  there  is  any  interest  or  apprecia- 
tion of  a  perceptible  result  beyond  the  actual  action  itself. 

If  the  foregoing  argument  is  correct,  it  follows  that  a  great 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  ACCOMPANIMENTS  OF  INSTINCTIVE  ACTION.  139 

deal  of  insect  behaviour,  at  any  rate,  is  not  conditioned  or 
caused  by  intelligent  consciousness  at  all.  It  may,  no  doubt, 
give  rise  to  consciousness,  the  consciousness  of  the  movement 
itself,  such  as  we  experience  ourselves  in  the  case  of  reflex 
action.  That  can  hardly  be  proved  or  disproved,  because 
consciousness  of  this  kind  does  not,  of  course,  directly  affect 
the  movement  itself,  and  therefore  cannot  be  inferred  from 
any  characteristic  of  the  movement.  With  regard  to  the 
consciousness  of  the  stimulus  object,  the  caterpillar  which 
the  wasp  seizes,  for  instance,  there  may  be  consciousness  of 
that,  of  a  sort.  But  it  does  not  rise  to  anything  that  we  can 
call  intelligent  consciousness.  And  it  does  not  seem  absolutely 
necessary  to  suppose  the  presence  of  consciousness  at  all. 
The  facts  are  equally  consistent  with  the  view  that  the 
physical  action  of  the  visible  object  on  the  sense-organ  of  the 
animal  translates  itself  at  once  into  the  appropriate  action, 
without  the  accompaniment  of  the  psychological  experience 
which  we  call  awareness  of  the  object  in  our  own  case.  The 
one  kind  of  consciousness  which  it  does  seem  most  natural  to 
ascribe  to  the  insect  is  a  vague  feeling  of  uneasiness  and  dis- 
satisfaction when  the  action,  once  started,  is  checked  or 
hindered  by  some  physical  obstruction.  And  it  might  be 
possible  to  work  out  a  view  on  this  basis,  developing  a  hint  of 
Bergson's,  according  to  which  consciousness  would  only  arise 
when  instinctive  action  failed  to  complete  itself.  But  such 
a  view  would,  of  course,  be  pure  hypothesis. 

In  the  light  of  all  these  considerations,  what  are  we  to  say 
about  Dr.  McDougall's  view  that  the  essential  conscious  ac- 
companiment of  instinctive  action  is  emotion,  each  kind  of 
instinctive  action  being  correlated  with  a  particular  emotion  ? 
As  thus  simply  stated,  this  view  seems  to  me  to  have  been 
too  thoroughly  riddled  with  criticism  by  writers  like  Mr. 
Shand,  Dr.  Eivers  and  others,  to  be  any  longer  accepted. 
Obviously,  it  would  be  very  difficult  to  assign  a  special 
emotion  to  each  of  the  very  complex  kinds  of  action  performed 
by  insects.  But  even  if  we  consider  the  higher  animals  the 
view  is  hard  to  maintain..  It  has  often  been  pointed  out  that 
we  find  different  emotions  accompanying  the  same  action  and 
different  actions  accompanying  the  same  emotion.  But  the 
criticisms  of  the  view  go  deeper  than  this.  For  they  raise  the 
question  whether  actions  and  emotions  necessarily  accom- 
pany one  another  at  all,  and  whether  in  many  cases  at  any 
rate,  they  do  not  appear  as  alternative  and  even  mutually  ex- 
clusive reactions  to  a  particular  situation.  In  our  own  ex- 
perience, as  Mr.  Shand  suggests,  we  find  that  the  emotion  of 
fear,  for  instance,  is  felt  less  intensely  the  more  quickly  we 


140  G.  c.  FIELD: 

are  able  to  meet  the  dangerous  situation  by  action,  and  may 
even  not  be  felt  at  all  at  the  time.  It  is  when  we  think  of 
the  situation  afterwards,  or,  one  may  add,  when  we  are  pre- 
vented by  physical  circumstances  from  acting,  that  we  feel 
fear.  And  Dr.  Rivers  suggests  that  a  strong  emotion  of  fear 
would  rather  hinder  the  performance  of  the  instinctive  actions 
of  escape,  especially  if  they  demanded  a  series  of  difficult  and 
delicately  adjusted  movements. 

I  cannot  help  feeling  that  there  is  possibly  in  this  view  a 
certain  confusion  between  instinctive  actions  of  the  kind  we 
are  discussing  and  the  bodily  expression  of  emotion  which  we 
really  feel  as  part  of  the  emotion.  These  bodily  expressions 
of  emotion  may  perhaps  be  properly  described  as  themselves 
instinctive  :  they  certainly  share  many  of  the  characteristics 
which  we  ascribe  to  instinctive  actions.  But  instinctive 
action  in  the  strict  sense  is  almost  certainly  independent  of 
emotion  and  need  not  be  accompanied  by  it  at  all.  And 
when  we  are  speaking  of  these  bodily  expressions  of  emotion 
it  is  entirely  misleading  to  speak  of  the  emotion  and  the  in- 
stinct as  being  correlated  or  connected,  or  to  use  any  ex- 
pression which  implies  that  there  are  two  different  things 
with  a  relation  between  them.  In  cases  of  emotional  expres- 
sion, if  we  speak  of  instinct  at  all,  the  emotion  is  the  instinct. 
There  are  not  three  different  things,  the  emotion,  the  instinct, 
and  the  action  to  which  the  instinct  leads,  but  two  only,  the 
emotion  and  the  action  in  which  it  expresses  itself.  In  one 
of  Dr.  McDougall's  instances — the  emotion  of  fear  and  the 
instinct  of  flight — if  flight  follows  immediately  on  fear  as  the 
expression  of  it  and  has  that  felt  connexion  with  it  that,  for 
instance,  the  visceral  sensations  and  the  trembling  of  the 
body  have,  then  the  emotion  of  fear  is  the  instinct  of  flight. 
But,  as  we  have  just  seen,  it  seems  probable  in  most  cases 
that  the  instinctive  action  of  flight  is  entirely  independent  of 
the  emotion  of  fear. 

The  whole  question  of  the  emotions  of  animals  is  a  difficult 
and  interesting  one.  It  is,  of  course,  beyond  question  that 
many  animals  do  feel  emotion.  But  it  is  equally  certain 
that  in  many  situations  where  we  should  naturally  ascribe 
emotion  to  them  further  investigation  raises  doubt.  Is,  for 
instance,  the  care  that  some  insects  display  for  their  offspring 
accompanied  by  the  tender  emotion  which  we  usually  suppose 
to  characterise  the  maternal  relation  ?  Prof.  Washburn  re- 
lates the  story  of  a  wasp  feeding  a  wasp  grub,  who  finally 
cut  off  one  end  of  the  grub  and  offered  it  to  the  other  end  to 
eat.  As  she  truly  says,  it  is  difficult  to  suppose  the  presence 
of  tender  emotion  towards  the  grub  in  the  mind  of  the  wasp. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  ACCOMPANIMENTS  OF  INSTINCTIVE  ACTION.  141 

And  cases  not  so  far  removed  from  this  may  be  found  even 
among  higher  mammals.  What  evidence  are  we  to  accept 
for  the  presence  of  emotion  in  any  particular  case  ?  I  would 
suggest  very  tentatively  some  such  test  as  this  :  If  all  the 
visible  actions  of  the  animal  can  be  explained  as  being  part 
of  or  having  some  bearing  on  a  whole  course  of  action  leading 
up  to  a  result,  then  there  is  no  evidence  of  the  presence  of 
emotion.  If,  on  the  other  hand,  in  cases  where  we  might 
reasonably  expect  emotion  to  be  felt,  there  are  any  actions 
which  seem  to  play  no  part  in  such  a  definite  course  of  action, 
these  may  be  taken  as  possible  expressions  of  emotion  and 
therefore  a  sign  of  its  presence.  Such  would  be  the  move- 
ment of  a  dog's  tail,  indicating  affection  or  pleasure,  and  the 
similar  movements  of  a  cat's  tail,  indicating  anger  or  excite- 
ment. Of  course,  the  strength  of  such  evidence  becomes 
much  greater  when  the  expression  of  a  suspected  emotion  in 
an  animal  resembles  in  some  degree  the  expression  of  a 
similar  emotion  in  human  beings. 

A  whole  flood  of  light  is  thrown  on  all  these  questions 
by  the  experiments  on  animals,  such  as  those  of  Schrader, 
Goltz  and  Sherrington,  on  which  Prof.  Lloyd  Morgan,  in 
Instinct  and  Experience,  bases  his  theory  of  instinct  as  the 
work  of  the  sub-cortical  centres.  In  these  experiments  it 
was  found  that  animals,  from  whom  had  been  removed  that 
part  of  the  brain  which  is  usually  supposed  to  be  the  seat  of 
consciousness  and  intelligence,  were  yet  capable  of  move- 
ments which  were  far  more  developed  and  complicated  than 
anything  that  we  should  normally  call  mere  reflex  action. 
The  decerebrate  pigeon,  for  instance,  could  fly  and  avoid 
obstacles  in  doing  so,  could  eat,  could  peck,  clean  its  feathers 
and  so  on.  And  yet,  as  far  as  we  can  tell,  it  was,  in  Prof. 
Lloyd  Morgan's  words,  '  a  mere  unconscious  automaton  '. 
Unless  we  are  going  to  throw  overboard  the  whole  of  the 
physiology  of  the  brain,  the  conclusion  seems  inevitable  that 
instinctive  action  is  independent  of  any  kind  of  consciousness, 
in  the  sense  that  it  can  take  place  equally  well  without  it, 
and  is  not  caused  or  conditioned  by  it  in  any  way.  This  is, 
of  course,  in  flat  contradiction  of  the  views  that  we  have  been 
considering,  and  takes  us,  indeed,  very  much  further  than 
our  criticisms  of  these  views  have  so  far  enabled  us  to  go. 
And  yet  it  is  difficult  to  see  how  it  is  possible  to  avoid  this 
conclusion,  which  takes  us  straight  back  to  the  old  view  that 
instinctive  action  is  simply  more  complicated  reflex  action. 

Finally,  we  may  perhaps  gain  some  light  on  the  question 
by  a  consideration  of  our  own  experience  of  habitual  actions, 
say,  the  adjustments  of  balance  that  we  make  in  riding  a 


142  G.  c.  FIELD: 

bicycle,  or  various  little  bad  habits,  like  biting  the  nails,  etc. 
Here  we  have  actions,  sometimes  fairly  complicated,  which 
take  place  just  as  well,  or  perhaps  better,  when  our  interest 
or  attention  is  concentrated  on  something  else  altogether. 
There  is  certainly  no  feeling  of  interest  either  in  the  actions 
themselves  or  the  stimulus  which  leads  to  them.  They  are 
at  the  very  margin  of  consciousness,  and  probably  in  some 
cases  sink  below  the  level  of  consciousness  altogether. 
Certainly  they  are  not,  at  the  moment  of  action,  caused  or 
controlled  or  conditioned  by  consciousness  in  any  way. 

This  is  not  a  proof  that  instinctive  actions  are  necessarily 
of  the  same  nature,  unless  we  adopt  the  view,  to  me  unten- 
able, that  instinctive  actions  are  historically  derived  from 
habitual  actions.  But  it  does  afford  an  illustration  of  the 
kind  of  thing  that  our  argument  so  far  seems  to  show  in- 
stinctive actions  to  be.  And  at  least,  if  we  find  these  char- 
acteristics in  habitual  actions,  it  does  afford  to  us  a  sufficient 
refutation  of  those  who  say  that  it  is  impossible  that  instinctive 
actions  should  show  similar  characteristics. 

If  we  adopt  this  conclusion,  we  shall  clearly  have  to  modify 
some  of  our  ordinary  modes  of  speech  about  Instinct.  As 
applied  to  our  test  case  of  instinctive  bodily  action,  Instinct 
must  be  thought  of  as  a  general  characteristic  of  certain 
forms  of  behaviour.  We  may  describe  this  characteristic 
biologically  by  its  origin,  i.e.,  by  saying  that  it  is  inherited  or 
innate,  and  by  its  results,  and  we  can  describe  it  physiologically 
in  terms  of  the  particular  kind  of  bodily  and  nervous  structure 
which  conditions  it.  But  if  we  are  taking  the  strictly  psycho- 
logical point  of  view  and  asking  what  is  its  connexion  with 
conscious  experience,  we  can  only  describe  it  negatively  by 
asserting  its  independence  of  any  form  of  this.  Nor  must  we 
speak  of  Instinct  being  modified  by  intelligence  or  experi- 
ence or  habit.  Such  a  way  of  speaking  implies  that  the  be- 
haviour is  affected  by  one  or  other  of  these  factors,  and  yet 
still  remains  instinctive.  Whereas  on  our  account  just  in 
so  far  as  the  behaviour  is  affected  by  these  it  loses  its  char- 
acteristic of  being  instinctive.  Behaviour,  of  course,  is 
modified  by  intelligence  and  experience.  But  it  is  a  contra- 
diction in  terms  to  say  that  Instinct  is.  We  must  not,  on 
the  other  hand,  say  that  an  animal  is  necessarily  unconscious 
because  it  acts  instinctively.  We  can  only  say  that,  as  far  as 
the  animal  is  acting  instinctively,  its  action  is  not  affected  by 
the  presence  of  consciousness.  If  the  animal  is  endowed  with 
consciousness,  it  will  be  conscious  of  the  instinctive  action  as 
we  are  conscious  of  our  reflex  movements.  The  conscious- 
ness, that  is  to  say,  will  be  of  the  action  and  follow  from  it. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  ACCOMPANIMENTS  OF  INSTINCTIVE  ACTION.  143 

There  will  also  be  some  kind  of  immediate  consciousness  of 
the  stimulus,  but  only  as  that  which  causes  the  action.  There 
may  be  more  consciousness  than  this,  there  may  be,  for  in- 
stance, reflexion  and  intelligent  interest.  But  if  that  ceases 
to  be  a  mere  onlooker  and  modifies  the  action,  then  the  action 
so  far  ceases  to  be  instinctive.  And  there  need  be  no  more 
consciousness  than  we  have  described.  That  is,  assuming 
that  the  animal  is  endowed  with  consciousness.  But  the 
mere  presence  of  instinctive  actions  does  not  by  itself  neces- 
sitate the  belief  in  the  presence  of  consciousness  at  all. 

These  are  the  characteristics  of  instinctive  action.  It  is 
obvious  that  no  other  form  of  behaviour,  no  thought  or  feel- 
ing, for  instance,  can  share  in  all  these  characteristics.  A 
thought  or  feeling,  being  a  form  of  consciousness,  cannot 
be  described  as  independent  of  consciousness.  It  might, 
however,  be  independent  of  other  forms  of  consciousness,  it 
might  be  due  to  an  innate  mental  structure,  it  might  be  un- 
affected by  previous  experience  or  by  foresight  of  any  end. 
If  we  start,  then,  from  instinctive  action  as  the  limiting  case, 
we  can  see  how  far  any  of  its  characteristics  are  shared  by 
other  forms  of  behaviour,  and  then  decide  whether  they  ap- 
proach near  enough  to  it  to  have  the  term  'instinctive' 
applied  to  them  as  well. 


II.— AN  IDEALIST  IN  EXTREMIS.1 
BY  F.  C.  S.  SCHILLER, 

To  write  the  history  of  Neo-Realism  would  be  a  consider- 
able service  to  philosophy.  It  would  be  interesting  to  trace 
it  to  its  sources,  to  determine  its  points  of  departure,  to  study 
the  influences  that  moulded  its  developments,  the  aims  it 
envisaged,  the  conclusions  it  arrived  at,  and  above  all  the 
persons  that  were  the  authors  of  its  being  and  steered  its 
course.  A  similar  service  might  be  performed  for  Neo-Ideal- 
ism  and  many  other  tendencies  in  modern  Philosophy.  When 
this  had  been  done,  it  might  be  possible  to  show  that  they  all 
converged  towards  certain  points  on  the  philosophic  horizon ; 
or  at  least  it  might  appear  that  they  were  all  infected  with 
the  spirit  and  the  vices  of  the  age.  But  anyone  who  searched 
this  book  for  anything  of  this  sort,  for  the  continuous  narra- 
tive and  objective  treatment  of  such  a  history,  would  certainly 
be  disappointed.  He  would  have  mistaken  Dr.  Bosanquet's 
purpose  and  method.  His  book  is  not  a  history  of  philosophy. 
It  could  not  be.  For  philosophy  has  no  history.  All  great 
philosophers  have  always  been  agreed.  They  have  always 
meant  one  thing,  and  the  same  thing.  It  has  been  called 
O-M  or  O-N,  as  the  case  may  be  :  but  it  is  always  O-N-E.  As- 
suredly, philosophy  can  have  no  history.  Nothing  has,  that 
really  is,  and  is  really  true.  And  Dr.  Bosanquet  is  much  too 
wise  to  attempt  the  impossible. 

What  he  attempts  is  something  very  different.  He  sets 
himself  to  show  modern  philosophers  where  they  have  gone 
wrong,  and  to  rebuke  them  for  backsliding.  They  have  all,  or 
nearly  all,  strayed  from  the  straight  path  of  orthodoxy  that 
leads  to  salvation  in  the  One,  and  fallen  into  heresy.2  Not 
only  the '  new  '  realists  (Eussell,  Alexander,  the  American  Six), 
but  the  '  critical '  (especially  Pratt),  not  only  the  'new '  idealists 
(Croce,  Gentile,  etc.),  but  even  one  so  old  and  eminent  as 

1  The  Meeting  of  Extremes  in  Contemporary  Philosophy.    By  Bernard 
Bosanquet,  Fellow  of  the  British  Academy.     Macmillan  &  Co.,  London, 
1921.     Pp.  xxxi,  220. 

2  The  only  apparent  exception  is  Mr.  Bradley  ;  and  even  his  reputation 
is  preserved  only  by  passing  over  sub  silentio  his  coquettings  with  scepticism 
and  pragmatism,  to  which  I  devoted  an  article  in  MIND,  No.  95. 


F.  c.  s.  SCHILLEE:  AN  IDEALIST  IN  EXTREMIS.      145 

Viscount  Haldane,  come  in  for  more  or  less  direct  censure. 
The  most  pernicious  of  their  heresies,  in  which  the  extremes 
of  Neo-Eealism  and  Neo-Idealism  meet,  and  consort  with  the 
'untouchable  '  pariahs  of  pragmatism,  are  'moralism,'  '  pro- 
gressism'  and  'temporalism,'  i.e.,  the  belief  that  time  is  real, 
and  that  reality  can  change.  These  are  the  fundamental 
errors  which  the  spirit  of  the  age  imposes  (p.  100) ;  but  they 
naturally  annoy  Dr.  Bosanquet.  Still  he  contrives  to  write 
about  them  with  his  usual  urbanity,  more  in  sorrow  than  in 
anger.  He  begins  to  see  red  only  when  Absolutism  is  classified 
as  a  form  of  '  intellectualism '  (cf.  pp.  100,  114  f.,  198),  which 
he  resents  as  a  "  dyslogistic  epithet "  (though,  curiously 
enough,  he  uses  it  himself  as  such  on  p.  61 !),  or  when  it  is 
credited  with  a  '  block  universe ' — for  all  the  world  as 
though  the  inventors  of  this  harmless  phrase  had  called  the 
believers  in  it  '  blockheads ' !  With  these  exceptions  he 
keeps  his  temper  admirably,  and  naturally  excites  sympathy 
as  an  Athanasius  contra  mundum.  Here,  one  thinks,  is  a 
heroic  Hegelian  assuming  a  truly  tragic  posture  in  the  last 
ditch,  distressfully  beholding  the  cosmic  process  (which  never- 
theless is  wholly  rational  and  the  revelation  of  all  Rationality) 
not  only  continuing,  otiosely  and  sans  meaning,  after  its  secret 
has  been  completely  eviscerated,  but  actually  repudiating  the 
absolute  truth  revealed  to  Hegel. 

Dr.  Bosanquet,  however,  does  not  really  need  our  sympathy. 
He  should  be  imagined  rather  as  seated  aloft,  like  Olympian 
Zeus,  in  a  "  truly  speculative  attitude,  free,  concrete,  penetrat- 
ing and  widely  appreciative "  (p.  viii),  contemplating  the 
little  systems  and  contentions  of  fallible  men,  and  "  the  really 
startling  difference  and  agreement  between  the  Italian  neo- 
idealists  .  .  .  and  the  English  and  American  neo-realists  " 
(ibid.},  and  watching  "  the  neo-realist,  the  man  of  compara- 
tive science,  and  the  empiricist  everywhere  at  work  to-day 
.  .  .  building  One  foundations  l  of  that  speculative  philosophy 
whose  superstructure  already  exists  " 1  (p.  75).  After  that  it 
is  clear,  on  his  own  showing,  that  Dr.  Bosanquet 's  place  in 
Reality  is  Nephelococcygia,  and  his  time,  the  Divine  Night  of 
the  Absolute  that  follows  upon  the  Odtterddmmerung,  in 
which  (as  the  Master  hath  said)  all  cows  are  black  and  all 
donkeys  loom  alike.  There  is  need,  therefore,  for  a  search- 
light, to  flash  upon  whatever  looks  '  suggestive'  or  c  instruc- 
tive '  in  the  light  of  the  Eternal  Truth.  And  Dr.  Bosanquet 
makes  great  play  with  it. 

At  first,  indeed,  his  procedure  seems  a  little  arbitrary.     He 

1  Italics  mine. 
10 


146  P.  c.  s.  SCHILLEE: 

plunges  in  medias  res,  and  picks  up  a  doctrine  here  and  a  dictum 
there  from  a  philosopher  who  can  bear  the  label,  either  of 
'  neo-realist '  or  of  '  neo-idealist,'  and  compares  it  with  another, 
similarly  selected,  discoursing  about  them  in  the  pleasantly 
allusive,  but  somewhat  involved,  style  which  is  such  a  valu- 
able adjunct  to  a  philosophic,  as  to  a  prophetic,  reputation. 
But  as  he  warms  to  his  work  his  argument  grows  more  con- 
tinuous and  incisive,  and  in  the  end  one  feels  that  not  only 
has  he  made  out  as  good  a  case  as  anyone  for  the  "faith" 
(pp.  200,  216)  that  all  is  one,  but  that  he  has  advanced  a 
number  of  contentions  which  are  real  contributions  to  philo- 
sophic debate,  and  demand  examination. 

As  such  I  would  enumerate  (1)  the  exposition  of  the  onto- 
logical  argument  in  chapters  ii.-iv.,  (2)  the  discussion  of 
'  7  +  5  =  12 '  in  chapter  v.,  (3)  the  criticism  of  progress,  (4) 
the  necessity  of  the  all-inclusive  system  or  whole,  and  (5)  the 
ultimate  inconceivability  of  change  and  time. 

(1)  Dr.  Bosanquet  is  fully  aware  that  the  '  ontological ' 
argument  is  essential  to  his  contentions.  He  has  to  prove  it 
'  sound '  in  principle  (p.  48).  He  has  to  remove  its  restriction 
to  the  existence  of  God  (p.  83).  He  has  to  show  that  "  every 
essence  has  in  some  degree  a  claim l  and  nisus  to  existence  " 
(p.  75),  and  that  "every  alleged1  essence,  every  distinct 
thought,  carries  with  it,  in  virtue  of  its  special  nature,  a 
certain  claim1  to  find  itself  in  reality"  (p.  98).  He  has, 
lastly,  to  show  that  it  is  "  possible  to  make  a  valid l  inference 
from  essence  to  existence"  (p.  76). 

To  prove  these  points,  he  undertakes  a  very  thorough  and 
instructive  examination  of  Spinoza's  embarrassments  (not  to 
say,  contradictions)  on  this  subject.  He  argues  further 
that  "  essence  involves  existence  where  affirmation  is  free 
from  confusion  "  (p.  82),2  and  that  "you  cannot  be  in  error 
about  a  reality  which  leaves  no  opening  for  misapprehension ; 
and  you  must  always  be  thinking  about  some  reality  "  (p.  84). 
He  retracts  indeed  the  confident  assertion  of  his  Logic  that 
"it  is  obvious  that  in  every  concept  the  intension  dictates 
the  extension  "  (p.  88),  but  still  maintains  that  "  when  we 
know  what  a  thing  is,  we  know  in  principle  whether  and 
where  it  exists,  and  how  many  of  it  there  are.  If  we  say  we 
know  what  a  sovereign  is,  and  not  how  many  there  are  in 
the  world,  then  we  do  not  really  know  what  a  sovereign  is  " 
(p.  89).  And  so  he  concludes  that  "  even  in  finite  things  the 

1  Italics  mine. 

2  Is  this  a  resuscitation  of  the  Cartesian  '  clearness  and  distinctness  '  as 
the  criterion  of  truth  ? 


AN   IDEALIST   IN  EXTREMIS.  147 

thought  demands  or  guarantees  l  the  fact,"  and  that  "  an  idea 
or  nature  or  essence  is  in  principle  self-contradictory  until  it 
has  given  rise  to  appropriate  existence"  (p.  98). 

Now  what  is  to  be  said  about  all  this  ?  In  the  first  place 
one  is  led  to  wonder  why  an  idealist  philosopher  who  has 
discovered  what  a  sovereign  (or  a  Rembrandt)  is,  and  is 
thereby  enabled  to  deduce  infallibly  "how  many  of  it  there 
are,"  does  not  at  once  become  the  greatest  authority  in 
finance  (or  art).  But  perhaps  he  has  discovered  also  that  he 
cannot  know  all  about  a  sovereign  (or  a  Rembrandt),  e.g.  its 
value,  without  previously  ascertaining  its  'extension,'  and  so 
its  rarity.  However,  it  is  pretty  clear  that  Dr.  Bosanquet  is 
right  in  recognising  the  wide  application  of  the  mode  of  reason- 
ing used  in  the  '  ontological  proof '.  It  is  not  merely  in  prov- 
ing the  existence  of  God  that  we  endeavour  to  pass  from  the 
presence  of  an  idea  in  our  mind  to  the  reality  of  a  correspond- 
ing object.  We  proceed  thus  whenever  we  try  to  apply  our 
ideas  to  reality,  and  to  verify  them  in  experience.  In  other 
words  we  do  so  most  of  the  time,  nay  all  the  time,  except  when 
we  are  merely  tracing  the  interrelations  of  entia  rationis,  as 
in  pure  mathematics.  But  we  do  not  ordinarily  accept  this 
claim  of  our  ideas  at  face-value,  without  discount  or  further 
examination.  The  fact  that  our  ideas  claim  to  apply  to  reality 
is  not  a  sufficient  proof  that  they  do  so.  We  do  not  ignore  the 
possibility  of  error.  We  admit  that  we  are  fallible.  So  we 
distinguish  between  a  '  demand  '  and  a  '  guarantee '.  We 
look  to  experience  for  our  guarantee,  for  a  confirmation 
of  their  claim.  We  realise  also  that  their  confirmation  may 
be  partial,  and  will  almost  certainly  be  gradual.  And  even 
though  our  ideas  may  be  wrong,  more  or  less  completely,  it 
is  consoling  to  think  they  are  capable  of  correction  and  im- 
provement. 

Now  it  is  precisely  this  whole  process  of  testing  the  claim 
of  an  idea  to  reality  that  the  '  ontological '  argument — and 
Dr.  Bosanquet — appear  to  rule  out  or  overlook.  The  whole 
paradox,  the  crux,  and,  I  venture  to  think,  the  fallacy,  lie  here. 
The  tendency  to  pass  from  existence  in  idea  to  existence  in 
reality  remains  a  mere  presumption,  instinct,  or  craving,  un- 
less, and  until,  the  claim  is  verified.  And  unless  it  can  be 
verified,  it  cannot  be  called  a  '  valid  inference,'  or  a  *  proof  '. 
Prima  facie  therefore  the  '  ontological '  claim  that  a  '  God ' 
exists  or  a  '  universe  '  exists,  because  we  have  somehow  be- 
come possessed  of  these  ideas,  needs  verification  and  con- 
firmation by  experience,  just  as  much  as  any  other  claim  to 

1  Italics  mine. 


148  F.  c.  s.  SCHILLER: 

reality.  If  any  philosopher  wishes  to  dispute  this,  he  should 
transfer  the  discussion  to  the  question  whether  some  (or  all  ?) 
claims  to  reality  are  self -proving ,  and  should  be  prepared  to 
meet  the  retort  that  they  are  only  impudent. 

This  is  the  real  question  about  the  '  ontological  '  argument, 
and  to  it  the  truism  that  wherever  the  conditions  of  going 
wrong  are  absent,  we  cannot  go  wrong,  is  merely  irrelevant. 
To  render  this  truism  significant  and  applicable  to  human 
knowledge,  it  would  have  to  be  shown  that  the  conditions  are 
ever  such  that  error  is,  in  point  of  fact,  excluded.  And  Dr. 
Bosanquet,  at  any  rate,  could  never  do  this,  so  long  as  he 
holds  that  human  thought,  being  finite,  must  necessarily  be 
in  error. 

(2)  In  chapter  v.  (p.  103)  Dr.  Bosanquet  tells  us  that '"  the 
whole  decision  upon  the  ultimate  reality  of  time  and  progress, 
and  the  just  criticism  of  moral  perfectibility  as  a  world-prin- 
ciple in  opposition  to  religious  self- transcendence  "  rests  "  in 
principle  "  upon  the  simple  addition  sum  7  +  5  =  12.  "  We 
start  in  elementary  logic.  If  12  were  not  the  same  as  7  +  5, 
the  judgment l  would  not  be  true.  If  it  were  not  different, 
the  judgment  would  not  be  a  judgment.  There  is  no  province 
of  knowledge  over  which  the  law  of  identity,  construed  as  the 
principle  of  tautology,  bears  sway.  There  is  no  region  of 
reality  which  can  be  interpreted  by  its  aid."  Hence,  so  far 
from  being  the  simple  sum  it  seems,  it  is  a  stupendous 
example  of  an  "  eternal  novelty,"  "the  expression  of  some- 
thing which,  parting  from  itself,  remains  within  itself,  and 
which,  being  always  old,  is  yet  perennially  new.  To  consider 
the  expression  impartially  is  to  recognise  in  the  simplest 
thought  this  inherent  connexion.  Here  we  have  the  open 
secret,  from  which  a  hasty  and  one-sided  philosophy  runs 
away.  ...  So  when  we  find  a  doctrine  which  judges  of  ulti- 
mate reality  on  the  basis  that  if  novelty,  progress,  difference 
are  to  be  achieved,  the  identity  of  the  whole  as  a  whole  and  in 
its  ultimate  character  must  be  abandoned,  we  know  where  we 
are.  We  are  simply  in  the  presence  of  a  blunder  in  elementary 
logic  ''  (p.  104).  All  the  progressists  commit  it,  and  it  leads 
them  erroneously  to  suppose  that  where  you  have  novelty  you 
cannot  have  sameness,  and  that  as  the  real  brings  novelties, 
it  must  change.  Whereas  "  when  once  for  all  the  principle 
of  the  judgment  7  +  5  =  12  is  mastered,  we  grasp  the  paradox 
at  once  of  reality  and  of  inference  "  (p.  112). 

A  pretty  paradox  this  of  the  '  eternal  novelty '  of  7  +  5 
-  12,  and  fit  pour  dpater  les  bourgeois  !  Nevertheless  the 

1  Italics  mine. 


AN   IDEALIST  IN  EXTREMIS.  149 

'  progressists  '  would  be  ill-advised,  nay '  hasty  and  one-sided,' 
if  they  were  routed  by  it.  They  should  tarry  to  examine  it, 
and  a  little  judicious  questioning  would  soon  deprive  the  sum 
of  7  +  5  of  all  its  terrors. 

To  begin  with,  they  should,  respectfully,  point  out  to  Dr. 
Bosanquet  that  7  +  5  =  12  was  hardly  a  good  example  of  an 
'  eternal  truth,'  because  it  is  not  properly  a  truth  at  all.  It  is 
not  properly  a  judgment,  but  only  a  proposition  (which  indeed 
is  what  Dr.  Bosanquet  himself  calls  it  on  p.  112).  And  even 
'  elementary  logic '  may  be  entitled  to  insist  on  observance  of 
this  distinction.  For  a  proposition  (or  in  Mr.  Kussell's  par- 
lance a  ' prepositional  function'),  like  the  whole  tribe  of 
mathematical  'truths,'  is  properly  a  form  of  words,  with 
blanks  for  inserting  '  variables '  according  to  requirements. 
It  is  not  properly  either  true  or  false.  These  are  qualities 
reserved  for  judgment.  'Truth'  is  its  glory,  'falsity'  its  be- 
setting sin.  But  a  proposition  is  merely  a  product  of  past 
judgments,  and  a  form  for  judging  future  ones  withal.  Nor 
has  it,  strictly,  any  (actual)  meaning.  No  one  can  say,  merely 
from  contemplating  7  +  5,  what  they  will  amount  to  in  a 
concrete  application  of  the  formula.  It  is  necessary  to  know 
what  are  the  7  and  the  5  concerned.  Experiments  with  drops 
of  water  and  with  fishes  will  give  widely  discrepant  results. 
And  even  with  fishes  the  results  will  differ  according  to  the 
species.  If,  e.g.,  the  scene  of  the  operation  is  a  pond  inhabited 
by  7  carp,  and  the  5  added  are  hungry  pike,  it  is  probable 
that  the  sum  '  12  '  will  be  a  very  temporary  truth. 

Clearly  then,  for  '  7  +  5  =  12 '  to  acquire  actual  meaning, 
and  to  become  (possibly)  true,  the  proposition  has  to  be  used, 
i.e.,  to  be  converted  into  a  judgment  and  applied  to  some  ap- 
propriate reality  that  admits  of  arithmetical  treatment.  It 
may  then  become  true,  for  the  time  being.  It  often  does, 
because  many  things  will  stand  arithmetical  treatment.  And 
every  successful  application  of  arithmetic  to  reality  will  have 
a  certain  novelty  of  its  own.  But  it  is  plain  that  in  this 
sense  arithmetical  truth  cannot  have  eternity.  It  is  strictly 
pro  hac  vice. 

It  can,  of  course,  be  taken  differently ;  for  mathematical 
'  truth '  is  not  as  '  simple '  as  Dr.  Bosanquet  supposes  and 
is  really  very  complex.  7  +  5  =  12  may  be  meant  as  a  sum 
in  simple  addition,  in  pure  mathematics.  In  that  case,  it 
will  be  a  deduction  from  the  conventions  of  common  arith- 
metic about  the  conception  of  number  and  the  operation  of 
adding.  So  long  as  these  conventions  are  retained,  it  will  be 
'true,'  i.e.,  deducible  from  the  system.  But  the  truth  of  the 
system  will  depend,  ultimately,  on  the  continuance  of  its 


150  F.  c.  s.  SCHILLER: 

applicability  to  reality,  and  if  this  should  fail,  its  '  truths ' 
will  be  affected.  Euclidean  geometry  has  recently  undergone 
such  a  deminutio  capitis.  Hence,  even  in  this  sense,  mathe- 
matical truth  is  not  strictly  '  eternal '. 

To  the  'law  of  identity'  the  same  remarks  apply  in 
principle.  In  the  abstract  it  too  is  just  a  verbal  form,  devoid 
of  meaning.  Which  is  why  logicians  have  found  it  so  hard 
to  say  what  its  meaning  is.  But  when  an  identity,  say  S  is 
P,  is  actually  asserted,  what  we  mean  is  that  though  per  se  S 
and  P  are  different,  yet  for  our  purpose,  and  for  the  nonce,  we 
claim  that  they  may  advantageously  be  identified. 

A  completer  analysis  of  arithmetical  truth  therefore  hardly 
seems  to  bear  out  the  claim  that  7  +  5  =  12  reveals  the  in- 
most Secret  of  the  Universe,  and  confutes  the  belief  in  the 
importance  and  reality  of  time. 

(3)  Dr.  Bosanquet's   objection  to   progress  may  be  dealt 
with  briefly.     While  admitting  that  "  the  place  of  time,  pro- 
gress and  change  in  the  universe  "  is  "the  ultimate  crux  of 
speculation"  (p.  125),  he  censures  its  "narrow  humanism" 
(p.  124)  ;  but  his  weightiest  objection  is  that  an  infinite  pro- 
gress "  must  necessarily  be  a  failure  ad  infinitum  "  (p.  206), 
and  involve  both  man  and  the  universe  in  the  fate  of  Tantalus 
(p.  57).    But  this  overlooks  two  alternatives,  (a)  that  progress 
may   be  real   without   being   infinite,   and  that    (as  I   have 
endeavoured  to  show)  becoming  may  attain  to  being  and  time 
to  eternity,  (b)  that  an  infinite  progress  is  not  necessarily 
bad.     It  may  be  worth  while,  if  the  quality  of  the  process  is 
good  enough.     And  whether  it  is  or  not  may  be  a  matter  of 
an  immediate  apprehension  of  value. 

(4)  The  existence  of  the  all-inclusive  system  or  whole,  of 
which  Dr.  Bosanquet  is  such  an  ardent  advocate,  rests,  of 
course,  on  the  validity  of  the  ontological  argument.     And  if 
further  it  were  frankly  admitted  to  be  the  expression  of  a 
craving  or  instinct,  nothing  more  would  need  to  be  said  about 
it.     It  would  rank  merely  with  "  the  unity  which  is  grasped 
by  faith  "  (p.  200),  and  the  other  manifestations  of  the  will 
to  believe.     But  it  is  clear  that  to  Dr.   Bosanquet  it  is  very 
much  more  than  this.     It  is  for  him  an  absolute  fact  and  a 
necessity  of  thought  that  all  systems  must  be  included  in  one 
system,  that  all  wholes  are  in  the  Whole,  that  '  all  that  is '  is 
a  *  universe  ' :  nor  does  he  hesitate  to  speak  repeatedly  of  the 
Whole  as  'infinite'  (pp.  114,  183,  188,  201,  209,  etc.).     Even 
the  strictly  individual   place-time  systems,  which  the  new 
physics  of  Eelativity  no  longer  profess  to  unify,  are  calmly 
assumed   to  form  a   '  total '   (p.    155) .      But   when  he   sets 
himself  to  reason  out  these  convictions,  he  is  singularly  un- 


AN   IDEALIST  IN  EXTREMIS.  151 

convincing.  Thus  we  read  (p.  177)  that  "  the  whole  cannot 
change.  The  whole  I  take  to  mean  the  universe ;  all  that  in 
any  sense l  is.  It  cannot  change  because  any  change  intro- 
duces something  that  is,1  and  this,  ex  hypothesi,  falls  within 
the  Whole.  The  Whole,  if  it  changes,  was l  not  the  whole, 
but  something  less.  All  that  is  includes  all  that  can  be; 
there  can  be  nothing  more  than  it." 

Here  it  is  clearly  assumed  that  '  what  is  '  forms  an  '  all,' 
and  that  any  novelty  which  any  change  introduces  must  be 
'something  that  is'  (timelessly) ,  and,  therefore,  was  from 
all  eternity.  But  these  are  the  very  assumptions  that  were 
questioned,  and  have  to  be  made  good.  In  arguing  in  his 
system,  Dr.  Bosanquet  is  plainly  arguing  in  a  circle  ;  and  it 
would  seem  that  the  only  way  of  avoiding  circularity,  viz., 
by  conceiving  the  system  as  '  open/  and  so  far  not  absolutely 
systematic,2  is  not  open  to  Dr.  Bosanquet. 

If  we  further  take  into  account  the  fact  that  there  is  no 
logical  route  from  the  partial  systems  (sciences)  to  the  all- 
inclusive  system,  because  the  selective  method  of  the  former 
is  antithetical  to  the  inclusive  procedure  of  the  latter,3  the 
validity  of  the  notion  of  '  universe  '  ceases  to  seem  self-evi- 
dent, and  begins  to  look  dubious. 

And  if,  finally,  we  endeavour,  with  Dr.  Bosanquet,  to  work 
out  the  meaning  of  the  universe  "  in  the  suggestions  of  life 
and  experience,  and  not  in  the  language  of  abstract  specula- 
tion "  (p.  177),  and  ask  how  in  the  concrete,  we  can  think 
"  all  that  in  any  sense  is  "  as  a  real  unity  worthy  of  the 
name,  we  shall  speedily  find  that  it  possesses  positive  features 
which  insuperably  resist  its  inclusion  in  a  universe.  For  it 
is  soon  seen  that  the  common  world  of  ordinary  life  is  not  a 
datum  but  a  (pragmatic)  construction,  compiled  by  ignoring 
the  claim  to  reality  of  an  infinity  of  private  worlds  (of  dream, 
imagination,  fiction,  illusion,  etc.).  Also  that,  as  even  this 
common  world  appears  to  be  infinite  in  space  and  time, 
nothing  can  be  predicated  universally  of  it,  i.e.,  of  all  of  it, 
that  is  not  liable  to  be  falsified  by  its  failure  to  exhibit  that 
predicate  somewhere  or  at  some  time.  This,  of  course,  was 
just  the  reason  why  the  ancients  regarded  the  infinite  as  the 
frustration  of  knowledge,  and  an  '  infinite  whole  '  as  a  con- 
tradiction in  terms. 

If  then  there  is  to  be  truth  about  the  universe,  it  cannot 
include  any  truth  that  is  liable  to  be  falsified  by  the  infinity 

1  Italics  mine. 

2  Cf.  my  study  on  Arguing  in  a  Circle  in  the  Aristotelian  Society's 
Proceedings,  1921. 

3 Ibid,  pp.  223-228. 


152  F.  c.  s.  SCHILLER: 

of  space,  time  and  change.  Pretenders  to  reality  infected 
with  these  cannot  be  truly  real.  They  must  be  excluded. 
So  must  a  great  deal  more  that  appears,  and  claims,  often 
very  insistently,  to  be.  Not  merely  evil,  but  all  finite  being 
as  such,  and  every  sort  and  grade  of  reality,  short  of  ultimate 
reality.  Only  ultimate  reality  can  be  real,  if  the  '  universe  ' 
be  real,  and  the  truth  about  it  absolute.  We  are  thus  con- 
fronted with  the  paradox  that  the  Whole,  which  was  designed 
to  be  all-inclusive,  excludes  pretty  nearly  everything.  But  it 
has  to,  if  it  is  not  to  become  merely  a  dumping  ground  and 
rubbish  heap  for  fraudulent  pretenders  to  reality  to  disport 
themselves  over. 

Even  this  does  not  exhaust  the  exclusiveness  of  the  '  all- 
inclusive  '  whole.  In  the  end  it  must  exclude  even  its  own 
votaries.  Not  merely  because  they  are  '  finites '  in  a  finite 
world  that  cannot  be  truly  real,  but,  quite  definitely,  because 
they  claim  to  apprehend  a  reality  whose  majesty  cannot  be 
apprehended  by  them.  They  thus  commit  Use  majeste.  For 
it  is  part  of  the  truth  about  the  Whole  that  only  the  Whole 
can  truly  know  The  Truth.  Partial  truth  must  be  partial 
error,  and  how  deep  that  error  goes  '  finite '  thought  cannot 
fathom.  It  can  know  only  that  the  Whole  can  never  be 
grasped  as  it  is,  viz.,  as  a  whole.  An  ungracious  and  un- 
grateful return  for  such  devotion  !  one  is  tempted  to  exclaim, 
until  one  reflects  that  ex  hyp.,  the  Whole  is  supra-moral  and 
1  beyond  good  and  evil '. 

Moreover,  in  virtue  of  these  same  difficulties,  the  finite  in- 
telligence, when  repudiated  by  the  Absolute,  is  bound  to  re- 
taliate in  kind.  It  is  bound  to  view  its  relation  to  the 
Absolute  also  from  its  own  standpoint.  And  then,  instead  of 
submitting  to  be  extruded  from  the  sphere  of  absolute  reality, 
it  must  refuse  to  enter  it.  It  has  a  right  to  point  out  that 
after  all  the  Absolute  is  primarily  a  theory  of  metaphysics 
and  that  no  metaphysical  theory  can  quite  shake  off  its  de- 
pendence on  the  mind  by  which  it  was  excogitated.  So  the 
absolutist  is  quite  as  essential  to  the  Absolute  as  the  Absolute 
is  to  him.  But  neither  relation  is  a  mystery.  For  when  a 
theory  in  its  conclusion  arrives  at  a  truth  which  negates  its 
own  truth,  the  simplest  explanation  is  that  the  whole  theory 
is  mistaken.  Hence  it  is  safer  to  leave  the  existence  of  the 
Whole  a  matter  of  faith  than  to  bolster  it  up  with  arguments. 

(5)  We  have  seen  both  that  and  why  Dr.  Bosanquet's 
*  idealism '  must  deny  the  reality  of  time,  change  and  finite 
being.  But  the  expurgation  of  '  appearances  '  thus  demanded 
js  surely  sufficiently  drastic  to  explain  why,  even  among 
idealists,  many  have  preferred  to  hold  that  the  universe  is 


AN   IDEALIST  IN  EXTREMIS.  153 

not  exclusive  of  time  and  change.  It  is  gratuitous  therefore 
to  ascribe  their  shrinking  from  Dr.  •  Bosanquet's  system  to 
"a  blunder  in  elementary  logic"  (p.  104).  And,  after  all, 
the  alleged  inconceivability  of  change  is  merely  a  prejudice. 
If  the  universe  (so  far  as  there  is  one)  appears  to  change, 
why  should  it  not  really  change  ?  If  '  all  that  is '  appears  to 
be  in  movement,  why  not  take  its  movement  to  be  real  ? 
In  spite  of  metaphysics,  eppur  si  muove  ! 

Nothing  is  gained  by  insisting  that  all  change  must  take  place 
ivithin  a  rigid  frame  that  changes  not.  On  the  contrary,  to 
postulate  such  a  frame  only  produces  an  unintelligible  rela- 
tion, an  intolerable  strain,  between  the  universe,  as  it  is  in  its 
'  essence,'  and  its  contents,  as  they  appear.  The  latter  are 
in  continual  flux,  while  the  former  is  immutable.  What  have 
they  then  in  common  ?  How  can  the  universe  support  the 
flux  ?  Why  are  not  stability  and  flux  intolerably  alien  to  each 
other  ?  No  visible  or  conceivable  kinship  can  be  traced  be- 
tween them.  That  they  belong  together  is  a  mere  allegation. 
In  short  Dr.  Bosanquet  seems  wantonly  to  have  involved 
himself  in  the  old  crux  of  how  an  immutable  *  substance  '  is 
related  to  its  changing  '  accidents  ' ;  to  which  the  answer  is 
that  the  accidents  need  no  support,  and  the  substance  is  in- 
supportable. 

Nor,  on  the  other  hand,  does  Dr.  Bosanquet  seem  to  see 
how  paradoxical  and  incredible  his  doctrine  is.  Bit  by  bit  it 
dissolves  away  all  that  is  deemed  real  in  the  ordinary  senses  of 
the  word,  and  leaves  the  philosopher  alone  with  the  All-One. 
And  then  it  dissolves  away  the  philosopher  as  well,  and  leaves 
the  One  devoid  of  content.  Instead  of  showing  reality  as  aris- 
ing out  of  nothing  and  consolidating  into  being  out  of  becoming, 
it  passes  from  being  into  becoming  and  out  of  it  into  nothing- 
ness. It  is  mere  Eleaticism,  or  worse.  If  a  human  touch  is 
admitted  into  this  grandiose  Creed  of  Disillusionment,  it  be- 
comes the  old  Indian  doctrine  of  Maya,  the  Veil  of  Illusion 
which  nothing  mortal,  nothing  finite,  may  pierce.  Behind 
this  veil,  we  are  told  (on  the  authority  of  an  eminent  finite 
thinker)  dwells  an  eternal  Absolute.  '  Of  Being,'  we  ask  '  or 
Nothingness '  ?  In  either  case,  credat  Judceus  !  And  we 
have  at  least  the  consolation  that  the  Veil  of  Maya  enfolds 
us  all,  clings  closely,  and  is  not  easily  rent :  indeed  Dr.  Bosan- 
quet is  likely  to  find  that  he  has  not  enough  of  the  illusion 
called  '  time '  wholly  to  dissipate  the  illusions  called  '  morality  ' 
and  '  progress  '. 


III.— IMAGINISM  AND  THE  WORLD-PROCESS. 

(With  special  reference   fco   Prof.   Mackenzie's  remarks  in  MIND,  Oct., 

1921.) 

By  DOUGLAS  FAWCETT. 

"  WE  have  to  inquire  whether  imagination  combined  with 
consciousness  may  not  be  the  same  thing  as  memory,  wit, 
power  of  discrimination,  and  perhaps  even  identical  with 
understanding  and  Keason.  Though  logic  is  not  capable  of 
deciding  whether  a  fundamental  power  actually  exists,  the 
idea  of  such  a  power  is  the  problem  involved  in  a  systematic 
representation  of  such  a  multiplicity  of  powers." — Kant, 
cited  by  Prof.  Norman  Kemp  Smith  in  his  Commentary  to 
Kant's  Critique  of  Pure  Eeason,  page  474. 

"  Underneath  all  the  reasoning,  inductions,  deductions, 
calculations,  demonstrations,  methods  and  logical  apparatus 
of  every  sort,  there  is  something  animating  them  that  is  not 
understood,  that  is  the  work  of  that  complex  operation — the 
constructive  imagination." — Ribot,  Essay  on  the  Creative 
Imagination  (Open  Court  Cpy.),  page  247. 

"  It  is  knowledge  of  structural  form,  and  not  knowledge  of 
content.  All  through  the  physical  world  runs  that  unknown 
content,  which  must  surely  be  of  the  stuff  of  our  conscious- 
ness. Here  is  a  hint  of  aspects  deep  within  the  world  of 
physics,  and  yet  unattainable  by  the  methods  of  physics. "- 
Prof.  Eddington  on  the  "  empty  shell  "  of  physics.  Space, 
Time,  and  Gravitation,  page  200. 

The  limits  of  hypotheses,  let  us  say  with  Mill,1  are  the 
limits  of  imagining  :  of  that  private  imagining  which  takes 
shape  in  abstract  concept  and  pictorial  "image"  alike.  And 
metaphysics  is  therefore  to  this  extent,  what  Ribot  calls  it, 
a  "  work  of  imagination,  superimposed  on  works  of  imagina- 
tion". Further  underneath  all  the  closely-knit  deductions 
and  logical  procedure,  whereby  hypotheses  are  applied  and 
tested,  lies  this  same  creative  imagining.  Nay,  all  reasoning, 

1  Logic,  Book  III.,  ch.  xiv.,  §  4.  Cf.  also  Mach,  Popular  Scientific 
Lectures  (Open  Court  Cpy.)  3rd  ed.,  pp.  228-229. 


DOUGLAS  FAWCETT  :    IMAGINISM  AND  THE  WORLD-PROCESS.    155 

whether  abstract  or  comparatively  concrete,  which  is  not 
verbal  or  merely  simulated  in  symbol,  implies  imagining  ;  its 
distinctive  service  lies  in  its  value  as  a  "  means  of  control  and 
proof"  (Eibot)  ;  as  the  "harmonising  controlling  force'* 
which  Bertrand  Russell,  perhaps  hardly  aware  of  the  vast 
significance  of  the  step,  subordinates  to  "  vision  ".  Reason, 
with  its  guiding  logic,  seems  a  secondary  creation  advantag- 
ing only  finite  sentients,  miserably  supplied  with  direct  or 
immediate  knowledge,  who  have  to  infer.  We  find  again, 
thinks  Ribot,  that  imagining  "  penetrates  every  part  of  our 
life,  whether  individual  or  collective,  speculative  or  practical, 
in  all  its  forms — it  is  everywhere  ".l  We  can  follow  it  from 
the  realm  of  the  "logical"  or  "abstract"  imagination,  on 
which  Russell  rests  pure  mathematics,2  to  that  of  the  work- 
aday sense-world3  or  even  to  this  and  that  sense-datum  as 
"  constructively  "  perceived.  Thus  far  preludial  empirical 
research.  This  strange  pervasiveness  must  needs  prompt 
inquiry.  And,  noting  the  neglect  of  imagination  by  most 
students,  we  are  not  to  be  surprised  if,  as  we  fare  forward,  a 
new,  and  perhaps  to  some  unwelcome,  horizon  shall  rise 
slowly  into  view. 

Creative  (as  well  as  conservative  or  reproductive)  imagining 
has  been  dismissed  airily,  e.g.,  by  Nordau,  as  "  a  special  case 
of  the  general  psychological  law  of  association".  Thirty 
years  ago,  fresh  from  the  glamour  of  Mill,  Bain,  and  their  kin, 
I  could  have  said  the  same.  But  the  difficulties  raised  by 
*  law,' '  association,' '  associable  units,'  '  retentiveness,' '  trans- 
formability  of  unit '  and  so  forth  are  too  formidable  ;  and  as- 
sociationism  in  its  popular  forms  cannot  stand.  In  this  case, 
as  in  that  of  the  truth-problem,  there  is  no  getting  very  far 
towards  a  solution  without  metaphysics.  The  riddle  of 
cosmic  creation  and  conservation  must  be  read  ;  failing  which 
psychology,  '  physiological '  and  other,  will  yield  only  a  pro- 
visional solution,  a  naive  economy  of  thinking  rather  than 
truth.  Creation  and  conservation  within  mere  human  ex- 
perience cannot  be  understood,  unless  we  have  first  grasped 
their  character  as  they  obtain  on  the  great  scale.  The  very 
"sensations"  and  "images,"  on  which  so  much  stress  has 

1  Essay  on  the  Creative  Imagination  (Open  Court  Cpy.),  p.  332. 

2  Cf.  Our  Knowledge  of  the  External  World,  p.  241.     It  is  imagination 
which  frees  him  from  the  tyranny  of  phenomena. 

:J  Cf.  Whitehead.  "  What  are  the  crude  deliverances  of  sensible  experi- 
ence, apart  from  that  world  of  imaginative  reconstruction  which  for  each 
of  us  has  the  best  claim  to  be  called  the  real  world  ? "  Organisation  of 
Thought,  p.  212.  The  "crude  deliverances"  are  gifts  of  the  world- 
imagining. 


156  DOUGLAS  FAWCETT: 

been  laid,  are,  to  rny  thinking,  just  mythological.  I  cannot 
develop  this  statement  farther  at  the  moment,  and  to  oppose 
it  to  mere  popular  thinking  in  passing  must  suffice.1 

Such  explanation,  as  Nordau  and  others  favour,  per 
ignotius  need  not  delay  us.  It  did  not  satisfy  even  the 
master  associationist  Hume,  for  whom  imagination  was  "  a 
kind  of  magical  faculty  in  the  soul  "  (Treatise,  i.,  §  7),  inexpli- 
cable "  by  the  greatest  efforts  of  human  understanding "  ; 
and  it  will  be  recalled  that  for  Hume  this  magical  power 
"holds  the  field  even  when  the  ego  and  the  notion  of  cause 
are  under  fire!  However  even  for  Hume  imagination  re- 
mains in  the  main  a  faculty ;  is  the  imagination,  ordinarily 
so-called,  of  the  psychologist  which,  however  pervasive,  is 
still  only  a  phase  of  our  being.  Hume  too  had  probably 
only  creative  imagining  in  view,  being  impressed  by  the 
seemingly  spontaneous  generation  of  novelty  in  this  domain. 
Nevertheless  he  prepares  us  to  consider  a  further  issue. 
There  is  surely  a  well-spring  of  creation,  of  originative 
power,  a  source  of  new  beginnings,  rising  in  this  so-called 
1  faculty '.  This  at  least  we  are  intimately  aware  of  when 
we  invent  aeroplanes,  pen  poems,  or  summon  an  infinite 
number  of  infinite  numbers  from  the  vasty  deep ;  salient 
examples  these,  it  may  be,  of  a  creativity  that  invades  us  in 
myriads  of  forms.  What  now  if  imagination,  ordinarily 
so-called,  the  phase  merely  of  our  being  to  which  the  psy- 
chologist, poet  and  plain  man  ascribe  that  name,  continues, 
comparatively  untransformed,  an  activity  that  underlies  the 
entire  psychological  individual ;  what  if  it  is  the  witness  of  a 
wider  imagining,  of  Kant's  suggested  "  fundamental  power,"  2 
at  the  base  of  my  sentient  life  ;  of  the  stern  on  which  all  the 
phases  of  my  psychical  being  alike  have  flowered?  This 
residual  tract  of  the  "  fundamental  power  "  (elsewhere  all  but 
lost  to  sight  in  its  creations),  refuses,  shall  we  say,  to  camou- 
flage itself.  It  resembles — the  analogy  is  a  remote  one — the 
germ-plasm  which  gives  rise  to  all  the  body-tissues  and  yet 
in  one  quarter  of  these  differentiated  tissues  maintains  itself 
more  or  less  unaltered.  Are  we  looking  at  a  waterhole  in  a 
hummocky  floe  of  set,  conservative  forms  ?  The  suggestion 
surely  is  an  attractive  one,  so  why  not  exploit  it  ?  We  have 
reached  the  peak  in  Darien  whence  Imaginism,  that  ocean 
of  grandiose  interests,  can  be  glimpsed. 

For   we   need   not   stop  here.      The   hypothesis   widens. 

1  The  processes,  discussed  conveniently  as  "  association,"  will  concern 
a  part  of  my  work  on  the  Individual. 

2  See  citation  heading  this  paper. 


IMAGINISM   AND   THE   WORLD-PROCESS.  157 

Perhaps  this  "fundamental  power"  at  the  roots  of  finite 
sentients  is  of  basic  importance,  or  even  fundamental,  in  the 
universe.  Those  who  regard  intellect  and  its  logic  as  evolved 
in  the  time-process,  but  desire,  withal,  to  believe  in  a  spiritual 
universe,  are  to  be  heartened.  Averse,  perhaps,  from 
Schopenhauer's  Will  and  Bergson's  filan  Vital  (a  formal 
concept  which  recognises  indeed  creative  evolution,  but  leaves 
its  character  unread) 1  disillusioned  metaphysicians  can  pre- 
pare for  an  adventure.  Not  in  a  blind  Will  nor  a  vague 
"  life  "  impulse,  but  perhaps  in  Divine  Imagining  lies  the 
clue.  And,  with  this  clue  in  hand,  we  may  decide  further 
that  philosophies  of  the  Unconscious  are  without  sting. 
Divine  Imagining  at  any  rate  is  not  a  dark  Schellingian 
"  Immemorial  Being"  ;  It  conscires.  The  verj'  '  activity  '  or 
'  energy '  of  the  universe,  of  which  we  read  in  the  pages  of 
Fichte  and  Hegel,  is,  perhaps  —  just  consciring.  Eussell 
tells  us  that  the  thinker's  business  is  not  so  much  to  argue  as 
to  get  his  readers  to  "  see  "  as  he  sees.  Well :  "  see  "  what 
Divine  Imagining  stands  for,  and  the  world  of  mathematical 
atheism  and  mere  naturalistic  realism  has  vanished  for  aye. 

Kant's  system,  an  awkward  monster  well  worthy  of  the 
bantering  of  William  James,  had  to  die.  But,  like  the  Norse 
Giant  Ymir  from  whose  death  and  decay  sprang  the  busy 
worlds,  it  broke  up  into  live,  but  fiercely  opposed,  intellectual 
forces  whose  clash  was  to  subserve  progress.  Fichte, 
Schopenhauer,  Hegel  and  Herbart  are  combatants  all  of 
whom,  strange  to  say,  find  their  inspiration  in  the  '  Critiques '. 
And  we  new  imaginists,  even  though  we  got  our  inspiration 
elsewhere — perhaps  as  a  genial  intuition  or  '  philosophic 
vision,'  as  Bertrand  Eussell  would  put  it,  after  exploiting  all 
other  tolerable  rival  aper9us  in  metaphysics — are  glad 
that  Kant's  suggestion  can  be  quoted  in  our  support.  There 
are  so  many  sluggish-minded,  conservative  folk,  professors  of 
academic  routine,  who  can  never  appreciate  a  point  of  view 
for  which  old-established  authority,  dogmatic  or  philosophic, 
cannot  be  cited.  Kant,  indeed,  had,  it  would  seem,  only 
finite  sentients  in  view,  and  he  left  his  suggestion  only  in 
part  exploited.  Still,  apart  from  the  concept  of  the  "  funda- 
mental power,"  productive  (as  opposed  to  empirical)  imagin- 
ation "buried  deep  in  the  soul"  figures  prominently  as  a 
factor  in  his  account  of  knowledge.  Later  again  in  Fichte's 
explanation  of  natural  objects — noumena  being  now  dis- 
avowed— this  pre-empirical  productive  imagination  acquires 

1  An  *  imperious  impulse  to  create  '  is  no  more  instructive  than  would 
be  the  derivation  of  change  from  psychical  "  force  " — a  word. 


158  DOUGLAS   FAWCETT  : 

a  cosmic  range.  Cosmic  in  range,  too,  is  the  Phantasie 
of  Frohschammer,  but  it  remains,  nevertheless,  only  a  factor. 
It  is  not  the  sole  ground  of  reality  :  e.g.,  it  does  not  include 
God  and  the  Ideas,  while  we  are  still  refused  that  real  novelty 
which  creative  evolution  implies.  These  two  defects  have 
vanished  from  Imaginism  as  it  is  conceived  to-day.  Thus 
(1)  Divine  Imagining,  in  its  modes  and  transformations,  is 
sole  ground  of  reality.  It  has  been  called  a  '  mobile  Absolute,' 
but  '  Absolute/  if  we  are  to  respect  its  established  meaning, 
is  not  a  suitable  label  for  ultimate  reality  which  allows  of 
change.  (2)  Creative  evolution  with  its  ever-fresh  novelty  is 
recognised  in  full.  By  this  hangs  an  account,  in  part  of 
course  speculative,  of  the  beginning  and  goal  of  our  world- 
system  ;  and  an  attempt  to  understand  the  causal  dynamic 
which  this  displays.  The  writer  in  1893  hit  independently  on 
the  notions  of  creative  evolution  and  of  what  is  now  usually 
discussed  as  Bergson's  vraie  duree.  These  notions  seemed  to 
a  young,  and  no  doubt  "  cocksure,"  panpsychist  obvious,  not 
debatable  enough  to  be  argued  at  length.1  On  the  other 
hand,  lacking  a  suitable  metaphysical  setting,  they  proved 
sterile.  Creative  evolution  has  to  be  interpreted  as  an 
aspect  of  Divine  Imagining,  and  no  metaphors  or  symbols 
that  fall  short  of  this  concept  will  serve  our  purpose.  There 
remains  the  conservative  side  of  imagining — as  real  in  a 
cosmic  regard  as  for  us — rich  with  the  wealth  which 
prompted  intellectualists  to  posit  a  static  or  immobile 
"rational"  Absolute,  rich  also  with  much  else.  Such  con- 
nexions as  certain  idealists  and  even  new  realists  have  (often 
perhaps,  too  confidently)  called  "  eternal,"  can  be  credited  to 
this  conservative  side ;  there  is  no  need  to  dub  them  "  forms 
of  reason  "  save  that,  once  noticed  and  generalised  as  truths, 
they  serve  as  premises  for  human  reasoning.  Reason  and 
reasoning  are  evolved,  to  all  seeming,  along  with,  and  in  the 
interests  of,  finite  sentients.  Eeason,  so  boldly  hypostasised 
by  Hegel,  does  not,  as  Lotze  would  put  it,  systematise  reality, 
but  rather  our  ideas  about  reality.  Its  defects  are  such  that 
the  mystic,  treating  it  as  a  makeshift,  invariably  seeks  to  get 
beyond  it. 

1  Cp.  Riddle  of  the  Universe,  p.  321:  "Nature  ...  is  a  continuous 
creation ;  the  inarch  from  firemist  to  organisms  is  a  revelation  with 
something  wholly  new  at  every  stage  of  the  journey,"  and  for  the  vraie 
dur&e,  p.  273. 

"  Really  there  are  no  '  states  '  at  all,  but  aspects  of  a  mobile  whole  now 
raised  into  prominence,  now  relegated  to  obscurity  .  .  .  time  (primary)  is 
merely  the  streaming  of  a  many-hued  whole,  aspects  of  which  attention 
grasps  piece-meal  as  '  before,'  '  after,'  '  together,'  "  and  so  on. 


IMAG1NISM  AND   THE  WOELD-PEOCESS.  159 

On  the  basis  then  of  foregoing  remarks  the  hypothesis  of 
Imaginism  can  be  stated  as  follows  :  '*  Ultimate  reality  is  best 
viewed  as  imaginal ;  as  conscious  activity  (consciring)  which, 
as  embodied  in  content,  resembles  most  nearly  that  human 
experience  which  we  call  imagining,  conservative  and  creative, 
reproductive  and  productive  (or  constructive).  It  is  not  urged 
that  the  other  aspects  of  experience  are  " unreal"  or 
"  illusive  "  ;  it  is  contended  that  the  imaginal  aspect  suggests 
the  divine  world -principle  more  directly  than  do  those  others ; 
shows  it  to  us  less  transformed  by  the  creations  which  take 
place  during  the  time-process.  "  Keason,"  which  many  have 
set  up  as  the  Absolute,  is  an  instance  of  secondary  creation 
such  as  subserves  the  living,  and  the  living  well,  of  finite 
sentients,  but  which  has  no  standing  in  reality  at  large  such 
as  could  be  called  cosmic."  l  There  is  no  obscurantism  in 
this  attitude  ;  rather  a  simplicity  that  goes  straight  to  the 
mark.  A  contrast,  withal,  may  prove  timely.  The  universe, 
interpreted  according  to  the  analogy  of  reason,  yields  the 
Hegelian  or  rational  IDEA  ;  interpreted  according  to  that  of 
imagining,  the  imaginal  IDEA  or  Divine  Imagining.  But, 
while  the  former  solution  cannot  be  stretched  so  as  to  cover 
all  the  facts  of  experience,  the  imaginist  embraces  them,  as  a 
sequel  could  show,  readily  enough.2  It  accords  also  with  the 
intimations  of  poets  ;  serves  indeed,  when  developed,  as  Prof. 
Mackenzie  inclines  to  think,  to  remove  "  the  last  vestiges  " 
of  the  old  quarrel  between  poetry,  religion  and  philosophy. 
It  provides  the  utmost  possible  satisfaction  for  the  meliorist 
and  the  embittered  critics  of  our  drab  terrestrial  world.  It 
is,  therefore,  at  least  worth  being  mooted  and  may  justify 
itself  fully  when  the  '  tester '  of  pragmatist  severity  has  been 
allowed  to  work  his  will.  Hypothesis  unapplied  to  the  facts 
of  nature  and  sentient  life  is,  of  course,  idle. 

Imagining  at  the  level  of  the  human  sentient  is  as  familiar 
to  us  all  as  redness  or  cold.  Its  nature,  what  it  is,  alike  in 
the  spheres  of  conservation  and  creation,  is  revealed  to  our 
consciring  unmistakably  in  what  it  does.  But,  on  the  other 
hand,  we  can  never  be  quite  clear  how  it  does  it.  Its 
"  buried  "  features  are  always  lost  to  sight ;  even  the  conscious 
creation  of  a  poem  is  in  the  twilight.  It  resembles  a  spear- 
shaft  of  which  the  tip  only,  thrust  out  of  a  cave,  reflects 
the  sun. 

Imagining  in  the  sense  of  Kant's  "fundamental  power  "  at 

1  Divine  Imagining,  pp.  2-3. 

2<7/.   ibid.,   ch.    iii.,    "Positive    Vindication,"  and    later    illustrative 
chapters. 


160  DOUGLAS  FAWCETT: 

the  root  of  the  individual  is  alike  too  wide  and  too  "  buried  " 
to  be  dealt  with  as  verbal  definitions  require.1  It  subtends 
too  much  to  be  limited  as  this  or  that.  It  comes  most 
nearly  to  the  surface  as  that  phase  of  my  psychical  life, 
imagination  narrowly  so-called,  which,  pervasive  phase  though 
it  is,  the  psychologist  contrasts  with  other  phases.  In  this 
quarter  we  glimpse  that  '  psychical  form  of  spontaneous 
generation/  that  becoming  ex  nihilo,  which  is  the  mark  of 
real  novelty  and  figures  so  largely  in  my  account  of  creative 
evolution.  Something  arises  out  of  nothing  in  all  quarters 
and  times  of  the  evolutionary  process 2 — in  all  cases  of 
causation.  Writers  of  textbooks,  trying  to  work  with  scraps 
of  psychological  abstractions  and  oddments  of  physiology, 
have  never  done  even  imagination  narrowly  so-called  full 
justice.  "  I  surmise  from  my  reading  of  the  psychologists 
who  treat  of  this  that  they  themselves  were  without  this 
faculty  (imagination)  and  spoke  of  it  as  blind  men  who  would 
fain  draw  although  without  vision."  3  Yet  very  familiar  events, 
the  drawing  of  deductions  (all  creations),4  the  invention  of  a 
carburetter,  the  making  of  laws  of  science,5  the  marshalling 
of  dream-dancers  in  fancy,  or  the  floating  of  a  self-contra- 
dictory concept  which  the  mere  logical  intellect  cannot  ac- 
cept, show  the  character  of  the  power  at  work.  Small 

1  "Imagination  transcends  thought  in  that  it  makes  us  aware  of  the 
limitations  of  thought.     And  how  do  we  define  imagination  ?     We  fail 
utterly  in  attempts  at  definition.     Kant  may  deduce  forms  of  imagination, 
but  he  leaves  imagination  itself  deep  buried  in  the  soul  of  man." — F.  C. 
CONSTABLE,  M.A.,  "  The  Meaning  of  Consciousness,"  Quest,  January,  1921. 

2  Cf.  my   World  as  Imagination,  pp.  365-366,  and  p.  380  on  chance. 
Also  F.  C.  S.  Schiller  on  "  Novelty,"  a  paper  read  before  the  Aristotelian 
Society,  October,  1921,  p.  19.     u  Novelty  as  such  means  Creation  out  of 
nothing."     Hegel  also  said  that  the  statement  "From  nothing  comes 
nothing  ;  from  something  something  "  abolishes  becoming. 

"A.  E.,"  The  Candle  of  Vision,  p.  27. 

4  When  these  creations  are  not  methodically  made,  you  have  the  so- 
called  "  intuitive  "  thinking  of  Faraday  and  others.    'Cf.  Divine  Imagining, 
Appendix  §  1,  Logic.     And  in  this,  as  Silvanus  Thompson  said,  you  have 
something  "  more  akin  to  the  innate  faculty  of  the  great  artist  than  to 
the  trained  powers  of  the  analyst  or  the  logician  "  (cited  by  Prof.  J.  A. 
Thomson,  Introduction  to  Science,  p.  78).     Genius  may  reck  lightly  of 
method. 

5  "  The  laws  of  science  are  .  .  .  products  of  the  creative  imagination," 
Prof.  Karl  Pearson,  Grammar  of  Science,  3rd  Ed.,  pp.  34-35.     I  should 
express  the  situation  thus  :   The  connexions  present,  independently  of 
human  sentients,  in  the  imaginal  structure  of  Nature  are  re-imagined  by 
us  in  our  own  ways  as  practical  needs  dictate.     Hence,  among  other 
things,  the  invention  of  the  famous  Mechanistic  World  of  so  many  poets 
of  science.     Materialism  itself  is  only  a  drab  kind  of  poetry.     This  imagin- 
ative construction,  of  such  value  for  practice,  is  useless  to  serious  nature- 
philosophy. 


IMAGINISM  AND   THE   WOELD-PEOCESS.  161 

wonder  that  Hume  saw  magic  in  this  domain ;  and  good 
cause  that  we  should  look  deep  in  a  venture,  however  belated, 
towards  explaining  it.  A  degraded  form  of  a  universal  cos- 
mic activity  is  in  view;  but  it  has  not  lost  all  its  "  original 
brightness,"  and  shows,  in  Miltonic  phrase,  only  with  "  the 
excess  of  glory  obscured  ". 

This  is  no  place  to  repeat  the  vindication  of  Imaginism 
which  has  been  undertaken  elsewhere.  The  hypothesis,  just 
indicated,  has  to  be  amplified  and  then  tested  by  application  to 
the  domains  of  nature  and  finite  sentient  life.  There  is  no 
trifling  with  philosophies  of  the  Unconscious.  Divine  Imagin- 
ing, while  superpersonal,  conscires  ;  and  this  consciring  is  at 
once  the  awareness,  the  '  energy '  and  the  ultimate  continuity 
of  the  universe.1  This  ground  as  sustaining  (conserving)  and 
creating  imaginal  fields,  is  the  cosmic  will  of  some  writers, 
though  assuredly  not  Schopenhauer's  or  the  "unweeting 
will  "  of  Hardy's  Dynasts.  "  Will,"  however,  is  too  sug- 
gestive of  a  surd.  Further  Divine  Imagining  enjoys,  it 
would  seem,  not  that  stinted  balance  of  happiness  allotted  to 
Bradley's  Absolute,  but  bliss  as  "  ineffable,"  i.e.,  as  beyond 
available  human  comparisons,  as  the  veriest  mystic  holds  it 
to  be.  It  comprises,  too, — the  variety  native  to  imagining 
prompts  the  suggestion — innumerable  world-systems  besides 
that  one  in  which  we  live  and  move.  In  all  these  alike  the 
only  units,  properly  so-called,  are  centres  of  conscious  life. 

Divine  Imagining  cannot  be  equated  (as  was  the  Hegelian 
rational  IDEA)  with  Truth.  Truth,  if  representational  prag- 
matism is  right,  is  never,  "  self- verifying  ".  It  is  a  name  for 
a  collection  or  collections,  usually  most  fragmentary,  of  true 
statements  arranged  according  to  a  plan.  Such  collections 
arise  piecemeal  in  the  history  of  finite  sentients,  and  are 
mostly  very  poor  makeshifts  beside  the  realities  of  primary 
interest  to  which  they  refer.  Geology,  for  instance,  is  a 
triviality,  a  distorting  device  or  instrument  of  us  earthlice, 
beside  the  rock-aspects  of  the  planetary  complex  present  to 
Divine  Imagining.  Our  Universal  History  is  a  dance  of 
shadows  in  a  hall  of  words. 

Still  true  statement  cannot  be  merely  useful.  We  are  able, 
however,  to  blend  pragmatism  with  the  correspondence 
theory  :  correspondence  being  treated,  as  by  Prof.  A.  K. 

la Divine  consciring  is  Fichte's  'infinite  activity'  regarded  as  also 
aware  of  its  contents  ;  the  conscious  energy  of  the  universe,  that  which 
at  once  conserves,  creates  and  grasps  together  all  contents,"  Divine 
Imagining,  xxvii.  On  the  meaning  of  continuity,  assuredly  a  much  more 
thorny  question  than  some  of  our  mathematicians  believe  it  to  be,  cf. 
Appendix  §  2,  on  that  topic. 

11 


162  DOUGLAS  FAWCETT: 

Eogers  (MiND,  Jan.,  1919),  as  likeness.  There  is  corre- 
spondence between  truth-ideation  and  reality ;  and  should 
reality  prove  to  contain,  as  the  phrase  goes,  "  contradictions/' 
the  ordered  statements  about  it  will  have  to  comprise  them 
as  well ;  coherence  among  truths  is  thus  subordinate  and 
might,  arguably  at  any  rate,  be  misleading.  In  theoretic 
science  we  experiment  with  ideation  :  we  imagine  and  hy- 
potheses are  born  :  each  of  these  displaying  for  apperceptive 
needs  conservative  and  creative  factors.  Discussing  the  most 
primitive  organisms  with  Minchin  we  can  imagine  chro- 
matinic  corpuscles,  from  which  evolution  moves  to  the 
bacteria  and  the  earlier  forms  of  the  protozoan  cell.  These 
corpuscles  or  biococci  and  their  doings  are  creations  of  fancy. 
But  if,  on  search  for  them,  like  natural  objects  are  found  to 
penetrate  our  spheres  of  consciring,  behaving  as  anticipatory 
fancy  made  them  behave,  we  shall  say  that  the  hypothesis 
has  been  verified.  OUT  private  imagining  has  simulated  suc- 
cessfully events  in  a  wider  nature-imagining  in  the  respects 
that  are  relevant  to  our  purposes. 

Divine  Imagining  cannot  stand  to  Itself  in  a  relation  of 
correspondence  nor,  shining  in  Its  own  light,  does  It  require 
truth-shadows.  All  relations,  even  those  of  the  most  isolated 
evolving  world-systems,  presuppose  this  ground.  It  is  im- 
mediacy which  conscires  itself ;  is  not  the  truth  "  about "  the 
universe,  but  the  very  reality  so  called.  In  this  reality  are 
established  all  things  and  all  sentients  ;  and  we  may  say 
that  the  vision  of  Prospero,  as  welcomed  by  Imaginism,  has 
become  good  philosophy. 

Realism  is  sound  thinking,  but  it  is  an  idealistic  realism 
after  all !  A  "  naturalistic  realism  "  is  simply  lyrical  but  dull 
poetry. 

"  True  "  ideation  then  is  a  phenomenon  of  relation  within 
the  superrational  reality  which  is  Divine  Imagining.  And 
human  imagining,  not  verifiable  by  reference  to  a  sphere  be- 
yond itself,  is  accordingly  neither  true  nor  false.  This  has  a 
bearing  on  the  position  of  pure  mathematics.  "  In  a  conversa- 
tion concerning  the  place  of  imagination  in  scientific  work," 
says  Liebig,  "  a  great  French  mathematician  expressed  the 
opinion  to  me  that  the  greater  part  of  mathematical  truth  is 
acquired  not  through  deduction,  but  through  the  imagination. 
He  might  have  said  '  all  the  mathematical  truths  '  without 
being  wrong."  1  In  the  case  of  pure  mathematics,  wherein, 
as  Russell  declares,  "  we  never  know  what  we  are  talking 
about,  nor  whether  what  we  are  saying  is  true,"  we  have 

1  Cited  by  Bibot,  op.  cit.,  p.  244. 


IMAGINISM  AND  THE   WOBLD-PROCESS.  163 

creations  of  the  fancy,  wherein  there  is  a  conservative  side 
implied.1  The  deductions,  whether  methodically  drawn 
or  such  as  show  in  the  "intuitive"  thinking  of  Silvanus 
Thompson's  "  great  artist  "  of  science,  alike  illustrate  creative 
imagining.  And  the  resulting  imaginal  fields,  while  repelling 
by  rule  internal  contradiction,  are  not,  merely  by  fulfilling 
that  condition,  guaranteed  to  be  true.  Eeality  is  wider  than 
truth.  They  are  primarily  an  extension  of  reality  in  the 
same  way  as  are  new  suns  and  nebulae.  Their  creation  in 
our  imagining  adds  to  the  wealth  of  the  universe.  I  am  not 
concerned  with  what  we  discover  rather  than  create  ;  discovery 
taps,  of  course,  the  conservative  side  of  the  universe,  i.e.,  of 
Divine  Imagining,  already  noticed.  But  sentients,  even  when 
discoverers,  appropriate  what  they  find  creatively  ;  are  not 
inert  funnels  through  which  the  waters  of  insight  are  poured. 

Prof.  Mackenzie  has  extended  to  Imaginism  a  generous 
welcome  of  which  I  am  deeply  sensible.  The  rest  of  this 
paper  will  be  a  reply  to  his  main  criticisms,  all  or  most  of 
which  (as  indeed  he  himself  suspects)  rest  on  interpretations 
that  have  missed  my  meaning.  His  verdict  is  distinctly 
favourable.  Were  the  difficulties  connected  with  the  time- 
process,  evil  and  contingency  removed,  "the  principle  of 
creative  imagination,"  he  says,  "would  not  have  much  to 
fear."  2  The  principle,  as  we  have  seen,  is  also  conservative  ; 
thereby  place  is  found  for  those  so-called  logical  or  stable 
connexions  which  so  many  hold  immune  from  change ;  nay, 
despite  their  enduring,  as  quite  unsubjected  to  time ! 3  It 
remains  to  suggest  how  the  difficulties  can  be  surmounted. 

But  first  I  will  note  a  minor  consideration  in  the  regard  of 
Hegel.  My  critic  suggests  (p.  456)  that  a  "  spiritual,"  not  a 
rational,  Absolute  is  Hegel's  last  word.  Hegel,  however,  in 
the  Philosophy  of  History,  in  which  his  thought  is  more  con- 
crete than  usual,  reaffirms  that  Reason  is  "  exclusively  its  own 
basis  of  existence,"  the  "  energy  "  and  "  sovereign  "  of  the 
world.  And  surely  it  is  precisely  this  Reason,  which  passing 
into  its  self-externality  as  Nature,  closes  again  with  itself  as 
the  Absolute  Idea,  as  Spirit  Dialectic,  again  (I  am  referring 
to  the  text  of  the  review)  is  not  merely  our  way  of  discover- 
ing the  abstractness  of  philosophical  notions.  It  is  Hegel's 
"  universal  and  irresistible  power"  which  animates  Reason  in 

1  Gf.  Divine  Imagining,  p.  39. 

2  Prof.  Mackenzie  has  recently  modified  his  views  as  to  time  and  allied 
problems  in  ways  that,  he  believes,  greatly  lessen  these  difficulties. 

3  Cf.  Divine  Imagining,  pp.  114-121.     '  Timelessness  '  for  many  vague 
writers  seems  to  mean  no  more  th  in  freedom  from  any  possible  change. 
But  even  the  changeless  has  to  endure,  or,  shall  we  say,  to  be  sustained 
stably.     Conservation  (c/.  Postscript)  implies  a  yet  deeper  Creation. 


164  DOUGLAS  FAWCETT: 

all  of  its  manifestations :  the  self -movement  of  the  notion 
which  (since  Nature  and  the  sphere  of  Mind  =  "  applied 
logic")  shows  even  in  physical  things,  e.g.,  in  meteoro- 
logical action.  "...  We  must  not  suppose  that  the  recogni- 
tion of  its  existence  is  peculiarly  confined  to  the  philosophic 
intellect.  It  would  be  truer  to  say  that  Dialectic  gives  ex- 
pression to  a  law  which  is  felt  in  all  other  grades  of  conscious- 
ness, and  in  general  experience.  Everything  around  us  may 
be  viewed  as  an  instance  of  Dialectic."  1-  There  is  really  no 
other  principle  of  movement  with  which  a  rational  IDEA  can 
be  ensouled.  Are  we  aware  of  a  broken  vase  or  a  shower 
of  rain?  "dialectic"  has  to  be  the  blessed  word  invoked. 
Reason  has  become  veritably  nominis  umbra. 

I  suggest  that  the  real  "  secret  of  Hegel,"  overlooked  even 
by  Dr.  Hutchison  Stirling,  lies  in  this.  Hegel  started,  on 
the  basis  of  the  Categories,  with  the  hope  of  showing  that 
Reason  is  sole  ground  of  appearances.  In  doing  so,  he  was 
forced — such  was  the  pressure  of  the  reality  to  be  interpreted 
— to  exploit  Reason  as  if  it  were  imagination.  It  was  im- 
possible to  get  forward  otherwise  in  such  quarters  as  Nature- 
philosophy,  Aesthetic,  and  the  Philosophy  of  History.  And 
the  "  faculties  "  of  the  finite  sentient  cannot  be  treated  as 
"additional  specifications"  of  Reason.2  Strictly  speaking, 
too,  even  in  the  Logic  the  semblance  of  the  "  self-movement 
of  the  notion"  is  achieved  by  what  really  is  a  feat  of  the 
logical  or  "abstract"  imagination,  as  Russell  calls  it.  The 
initial  notion,  Being  or  "  underived  indeterminateness,"  does 
not  come  to  anyone  straight  through  his  primary  experience, 
but  is  a  command -concept  of  his  imagining,  a  novelty  which 
is  created  for  an  end.  And  the  successive  solutions  of  the 
"  contradictions  "  of  the  logical  series  flow  not  from  this  self- 
propelled  notion,  but  are  imported  into  it  by  an  inventive 
philosopher  who  is  reimagining  empirical  reality  as  the 
famous  "  realm  of  shades  "  which  we  find  in  the  Logic. 

And  now  as  to  the  question  of  time-process. 

We  are  not  considering  conceptual  or  homogeneous  time. 
Primary  time  means  certain  manners  in  which  contents  are 
present  to  Divine  Imagining.3  Hence  the  Kantian  time-sub- 
jectivism is  false.  These  manners  of  presence,  to  wit  dura- 
tion, simultaneity  and  succession,  exist  not  only  for  us  but  in 
the  wider  real.  I  have  suggested  how  they  are  interrelated 
in  the  case  of  a  world-system  both  as  it  pre-exists  to,  and  as 

1  The  Logic  of  Hegel,  Wallace,  pp.  127-128. 

2  This  phrase  of  Hegel's  is  illuminative.     Verbally  he  seems  consistent, 
but  he  is  capitulating  in  fact  to  a  plastic  "  fundamental  power  "  and  a  real 
time  process.  3  Divine  Imagining,  p.  106. 


IMAGINISM  AND   THE  WOELD-PBOCESS.  165 

it  falls  into,  creative  evolution.1  Prof.  Mackenzie,  by  the 
way,  questions  the  suitability  of  the  term  "falls".  This 
passage  into  creative  evolution  may  be  regarded  as  a  "  fall " 
or  a  "rise"  according  as  you  regard  it  as  a  lapse  of  the 
system  into  conflict,  division,  and  evil  or  as  giving  birth  to 
innumerable  new  finite  sentients  and  mediating,  to  their  final 
satisfaction,  a  '  divine  event ' : — 

Nay,  nay,  nay  ; 

Your  hasty  judgments  stay, 

Until  the  topmost  cyme 

Have  crowned  the  last  entablature  of  Time. 

O  heap  not  blame  on  that  in-brooding  Will ; 

O  pause,  till  all  things  in  their  day  fulfil ! 2 

The  cross-section  of  a  minor  part  of  the  creative  phase, 
such  as  that  of  our  planetary  sub- world  to-day,  inspires 
pessimism  ;  the  entire  process  can  be  vindicated  only  in  the 
result  which  resumes  and  exalts  it. 

The  time-relations  are  complicated  with  those  of  space. 
It  may  be  that,  in  the  case  of  an  evolving  world-system, 
space  or  coexistence  arises  within  the  time-process  as  one  of 
the  early  triumphs  of  the  imaginal  dynamic,  of  course  ante- 
dating by  aeons  the  appearing  of  finite  sentients  of  the  human 
sort.1  On  the  other  hand,  it  may  be  that  time-space  pre- 
existed to  the  creative  process  or  metaphysical  fall.  Who 
can  say  ?  But,  if  the  second  alternative  holds,  we  still  con- 
front features  of  content  in  Divine  Imagining  :  we  are  far 
from  that  topsyturvydom  in  which  an  empty  abstraction 
called  time-space  exists  substantially  in  its  own  right.  Not 
only  is  the  initial  state  of  a  world-system  conscired  :  it  is  also 
vastly  richer  than  any  discussion  of  time-space  could  suggest. 
It  is  an  inchoate  romance,  a  poem  of  that  golden  age  before 
the  clash  of  sentients  :— 

Corcordes  animae  nunc  et  dum  nocte  premuntur 
Heu  quantum  inter  se  bellum  si  lumina  vitae 
Attigerint,  quantas  acies  stragemque  ciebunt ! 

Of  course,  what  Prof.  Eddington  calls,  the  "  empty  shell  " 
of  modern  speculative  physics  can  help  us  little  towards  an 
understanding  of  the  real  psychical  continuum  of  Nature.3 

1  Divine  Imagining,  ch.  ix.,  "  The  evolution  of  Nature  ". 

2  Chorus  of  the  Years  in  the  Dynasts. 

3  We  are  considering  primeval  cosmic  time  and  space.     The  indefinitely 
many  discordant  time-series  and  distinct  spaces  of  modern  relativist  dis- 
cussions belong  to  the  realm  of  division  and  conflict  in  which  finite  per- 
cipients have  to  measure.     "...  What  philosophy  has  to  recognise  in 
scientific  relativity  is  simply  an  increased  degree  of  accuracy  due  to  the 
greater  exactitude  of  physical  concepts,  which  means,  again,  that  little,  if 
indeed  anything,  truly  metaphysical  is  in  question  at  all." — J.  E.  Turner, 
MIND,  Jan.,  p.  52. 


166  DOUGLAS   FAWCETT  : 

Here  as  elsewhere  Prof.  Pringle  Pattison's  remark  holds  good 
that  "  the  truth  of  the  poetic  imagination  is  perhaps  the  pro- 
foundest  doctrine  of  a  true  philosophy  ".  Let  us  make  use 
of  this  imagination  accordingly. 

The  metaphysical  fall  into  change  is  not  difficult  to  conceive. 
"  A  truer  image  of  the  world,  I  think,  is  obtained  by  picturing 
things  as  entering  into  the  stream  of  time  from  an  eternal 
world  outside  than  from  a  view  which  regards  time  as  the 
devouring  tyrant  of  all  that  is."1  For  "eternal"  here  we 
may  read  "conservative"  world,  while  we  must  be  careful 
not  to  whittle  down  time  to  succession  alone.  What,  how- 
ever, is  this  succession  in  our  imaginist  scheme  ?  It  is  not 
unreal,  a  show  merely  for  finite  sentients,  as  so  many  ab- 
solutists declare.  It  is  just  the  Form  of  Creation  :  an  aspect 
of  Divine  Imagining  and  consequently  as  ultimately  real  as  this 
fundamental  power  itself.  A  fixed  Imagining,  without  powTer 
to  initiate  change,  were  surely  an  absurd  principle.  To  be  is 
to  be  active  and,  as  active,  Imagining  sustains  and  creates. 
The  changing  of  creation  is  the'  very  time-succession  of  our 
quest.  And  with  the  arising  of  finite  sentients  in  this  chang- 
ing comes  the  creation  of  creators.  Observe  that  not  only 
creation  but  destruction  must  be  recognised.  A  static 
Absolute  cannot  scavenge  its  kingdom.  Not  so  this  protean 
power.  During  the  lapse  from,  and  return  to,  the  harmony 
which  is  beauty,  delight  and  love  there  arise  innumerable 
abominations  from  which  reality  has  to  be  freed.  Something, 
qua  novel,  becomes  from  nothing  ;  it  can  disappear  also  into 
nothing.  Superior  levels  of  consciring  may  cease  to  conscire 
it.  Its  support  fails.  It  vanishes  and  leaves  not  a  rack 
behind. 

Evil,  which  implies  conflict,  colours  the  realm  of  division 
— of  creative  evolution  ;  in  part  it  is  overruled  and  trans- 
formed in  the  real  time-process,  in  part,  however,  it  may 
perish  utterly  even  from  that  "  past "  which  conservative 
Divine  Imagining  sustains.2  "When  an  "  Eternal  Spirit,"  as 
Prof.  Mackenzie  calls  the  Finite  God  of  a  world-system, 
decrees  the  metaphysical  fall,  his  self-diremption  is  decreed 
therewith.3  He  remains,  "  with  excess  of  glory  obscured," 
a  Finite  God,  but  he  is  now  to  be  continued  also  in  the  minor 
gods  and  humbler  fragmentary  sentients  of  all  grades,  from 
psychoid  or  mentoid  upward,  which  the  new  evolving  world- 
system,  objectively  his  body,  includes.  Thus  the  very 

1  Russell,  Our  Knowledge  of  the  External  World,  p.  167. 

2  Divine  Imagining,  pp.  149-153.     On  Evil,  cf.  World  as  Imagination, 
pp.  566-604.  3  Cf.  £>ivine  Imagining,  pp.  225-227. 


IMAGINISM  AND   THE   WORLD-PROCESS.  167 

"creation  of  creators,"  which  Prof.  Mackenzie  desires  to 
accent,  arises  in  this  way.  Since  each  sentient  is  now  "  lui- 
meme  "  (c/.,  MIND,  July,  p.  461),  a  centre  in  which  novelty 
is  born  out  of  nothing,1  variations  of  all  sorts  will  arise.  The 
partial  dissociation  of  God  into  the  sentients  is  the  condition 
of  their  appearing  at  all.  You  may  call  this  appearance,  in 
Schopenhauer's  vein,  the  "fundamental  evil  "  or,  as  a  melior- 
ist,  you  may  be  hopeful  and  wait  patiently,  like  Hardy's 
Chorus  of  the  Years  "till  all  things  in  their  day  fulfil". 
But  at  any  rate  you  will  have  to  allow  to  the  sentients 
something  of  the  spontaneity  and  magic  that  belong  to  their 
source.  Hence  miscreations,  born  out  of  nothing  in  a  loose 
system,  account  for  much ;  for  the  merely  abominable  that 
subserves  no  wide  purpose.  The  many  useful  evils,  i.e.,  evils 
which,  for  a  long  view,  are  found  to  subserve  sentient  life, 
need  not  occupy  us.  They  justify  themselves. 

The  misunderstanding  as  to  '  chance  '  is  rectified  easily. 
'  Absolute  chance  '  is  not  being  argued  for.  I  am  noting  that 
to  a  basis  of  given  conservative  factors  there  can  be  added 
creations,  novelties  at  once  (1)  unpredictable  and  (2)  born  out 
of  nothing.  And  when  these  abrupt  beginnings  occur  on  the 
lower  levels  of  sentient  life,  we  have  to  reckon  with  an  "  un- 
determined "  element  which  may  work  anon  for  weal  or  woe. 
It  is  not  a  question  of  supposing  conditions  "  outside  Divine 
Imagining  "  :  it  is  a  question  of  creations,  of  which  innumer- 
able centres,  even  within  some  subordinate  demiurge,  may  be 
the  seats.  For  which  reason  I  described  this  '  chance '  as  a 
"  feature  of  imagining  as  it  works  on  low  levels  of  evolution," 2 
not  differing  therefore  in  kind  from  that  spontaneity  which 
shows  in  what  we  call  freedom  in  its  various  higher  modes. 

There  is  no  danger,  as  Prof.  Mackenzie  fears,  that  the 
creative  variations  will  ever  escape  control.  At  long  last 
one  aspect  of  the  cosmos  serves  to  balance  another.  And 
creation  is  limited  by  the  circumstances  on  which  the  novelty 
has  to  be  superinduced.  Imagining  "  improvises,  like  a 
Shakespeare  among  ourselves,  on  a  basis  of  given  conditions 
which  impose  genuine,  though  elastic,  restrictions  on  creative 
power  ",3  Consider  the  invention  of  the  game  of  chess.  The 
indefinitely  many  possible  variations  presuppose,  of  course, 
the  creative  ingenuity  of  players  who  are  realising  purposes. 
But,  however  brilliant  may  be  the  players,  their  creations  are 
limited  by  the  conditions  laid  down  in  the  rules  of  play. 

1  Vide  supra. 

2  Divine  Imagining,  p.  144.     See  also  World  as  Imagination,  pp.  377-385 
on  "  chance  ". 

2tfnd,,  p.  446. 


168   DOUGLAS  FAWCETT  :   IMAGINISM  AND  THE  WORLD-PROCESS. 

This  unpredictable  becoming  ex  nihilo  may  involve  grave 
disturbances  over  large  regions,  and  corresponding  difficulties 
for  the  finite  sentients  which  have  to  deal  with  them.  Hence 
'  trial  and  error  '  play  so  important  a  part  in  the  time-process. 
And  I  must  suggest  that  even  Prof.  Mackenzie's  "  Eternal 
Spirit  " — the  finite  God  of  a  world-system — may  have  to  ex- 
periment if,  relatively  even  to  his  own  system,  he  is  limited 
in  power  or  wisdom  or  both.  A  world-system  is  a  big  area. 
Nevertheless  its  God  must  not,  for  that,  be  equated  with  the 
Divine  Imagining  which  shows  alike  in  him,  in  the  opposi- 
tions with  which  he  contends  and  in,  perhaps,  indefinitely 
many  other  Gods,  and  systems  beyond  our  ken.  '  Trial  and 
error '  obtain  wherever  finite  sentients  have  to  adjust  them- 
selves to  their  surround,  even  if  some  of  these  sentients,  in 
virtue  of  their  power,  benevolence  and  wisdom,  are  entitled 
to  be  called  divine. 

POSTSCRIPT. — The  Ground  of  appearances  has  been  dis- 
cussed in  this  paper  as  alike  conservative  and  creative.  But 
conservation  (as  students  of  Descartes  might  urge  very  pro- 
perly) implies  sustaining  creation,  failing  which  the  stably 
sustained  would  vanish  and  leave  not  a  rack  behind.  Thus 
Creative  activity  dwells  in  the  deepest  depths  :  a  considera- 
tion quite  welcome  to  those  who  find  in  Divine  Imagining 
the /cms  et  origo  of  appearances.  To  be  is  to  be  created  or 
create,  or  both.  It  becomes  sunclear  why  Imagining  is  to 
be  substituted  for  the  immobile,  the  frozen,  spiritual  Absolutes 
of  the  past. 


IV.— EINSTEIN'S  THEORY  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

BY  H.  WILDON  CAEE. 

ME.  J.  E.  TUENEE  in  an  interesting  and  incisive  article  in 
the  January  number  of  this  Journal  (p.  40)  has  submitted  to 
detailed  criticism  the  argument,  advanced  by  Lord  Haldane 
in  his  Reign  of  Relativity  and  by  myself  in  my  General 
Principle  of  Relativity  and  articles  in  Nature,  that  Einstein's 
scientific  theory  is  based  upon  a  distinctively  philosophic 
principle.  In  common  with  many,  probably  with  the 
majority  of,  leading  philosophers,  and  with  a  few,  though 
probably  a  minority  of,  mathematicians  and  physicists,  Mr. 
Turner  holds  that  there  is  no  real  identity  between  the 
scientific  and  the  philosophical  principles  of  relativity.  I  do 
not  propose  to  examine  his  objections  in  detail  but  to  restate 
the  position  with  particular  reference  to  the  Gallic  attitude 
towards  the  mathematical  principle  which  he  and  so  many 
of  my  colleagues  profess  to  maintain. 

A  typical  instance  of  this  caring-for-none-of-these-things 
attitude  is  afforded  me  in  an  article,  entitled  "  On  my  friendly 
Critics "  by  Mr.  Santayana  in  the  Journal  of  Philosophy, 
22nd  December,  1921.  It  is  the  apologia  of  one  who  prides 
himself  on  a  certain  philosophical  detachment.  I  will 
quote  the  whole  passage.  "  I  have  no  metaphysics,  and  in 
that  sense  I  am  no  philosopher,  but  a  poor  ignoramus  trust- 
ing what  he  hears  from  the  men  of  science.  I  rely  on  them 
to  discover  gradually  exactly  which  elements  in  their  descrip- 
tion of  nature  may  be  literally  true,  and  which  merely  sym- 
bolical :  even  if  they  were  all  symbolical,  they  would  be  true 
enough  for  me.  My  naturalism  is  not  at  all  afraid  of  the 
latest  theories  of  space,  time,  or  matter  :  what  I  understand 
of  them,  I  like,  and  am  ready  to  believe  :  for  I  am  a  follower 
of  Plato  in  his  doctrine  that  only  knowledge  of  ideas  (if  we 
call  it  knowledge)  can  be  literal  and  exact,  whilst  practical 
knowledge  is  necessarily  mythical  in  form,  precisely  because 
its  object  exists  and  is  external  to  us."  The  natural  world 
which  he  distinguishes  from  "  figments  of  fancy,  interesting 
as  poetry  is  interesting,"  is  the  "  world  of  medicine  and  com- 
merce ".  That  this  is  actual,  he  says,  is  "  so  obvious  to  every 


170  H.  WILDON  CAEE: 

man  in  his  sane  moments  that  I  have  always  thought  it  idle 
to  argue  the  point  ".  I  am  ready  to  admit  that  every  man 
in  his  sane  moments  makes  this  distinction  between  the 
actual  and  the  mythical,  but  for  a  philosopher  on  the  ground 
of  such  a  distinction  to  accept  the  actual  world  uncritically 
at  its  face  value  appears  to  me  a  renunciation  of  philosophy. 

It  is  not  a  little  curious  to  contrast  this  marked  indifference 
of  a  philosopher  to  the  new  scientific  discovery  with  the  pro- 
found consciousness  the  mathematicians  express  of  its  funda- 
mental philosophical  significance.  I  have  in  mind  particu- 
larly Eddington,  Weyl,  Thirring  and  Einstein  himself,  to 
mention  only  a  few.  No  doubt  in  the  seventeenth  century 
when  the  new  discovery  of  Copernicus  was  winning  accept- 
ance among  men  of  science  the  orthodox  Scholastic  philo- 
sophers took  up  the  same  attitude  of  indifference  towards  it 
which  so  many  contemporary  philosophers  are  now  taking  to 
Einstein's  theory,  and  yet  the  whole  movement  of  modern 
philosophy,  which  arose  with  Descartes,  clearly  starts  from 
the  Copernican  revolution,  is  based  upon  it,  and  not  only 
historically  but  intrinsically  is  unintelligible  save  in  the  light 
of  it.  Prof.  Weyl  has  expressed  the  opinion  that  the  dis- 
covery of  Einstein  is  no  whit  inferior  to  the  discovery  of 
Copernicus  in  the  tremendous  consequences  which  follow 
from  it  and  in  its  complete  reversal  of  our  ordinary  conception 
of  the  nature  of  the  physical  universe.  This  is  no  exaggera- 
tion. To  me  it  seems  certain  that  even  the  most  brilliant 
scientific  achievements  of  the  nineteenth  century  will  in  the 
future  be  classified  as  pre-Einstinian. 

The  analogy  between  the  two  theories  is  in  itself  very  re- 
markable. It  may  be  illustrated  in  regard  to  quite  ordinary 
experience.  For  example,  everyone  knows  the  danger  of 
alighting  from  a  train  in  motion  and  also  that  the  danger  is 
proportionate  to  the  velocity  of  the  train.  Most  of  us  think 
that  the  explanation  is  simple,  and  so  obvious  as  to  seem  self- 
evident.  It  is  due  we  suppose  to  our  inability  to  keep  our 
balance.  It  seems  both  impossible  and  unnecessary  to  imagine 
an  alternative.  We  suppose  that  the  moving  system  of  the 
train  has  induced  some  subtle  change  in  our  mentality,  form- 
ing a  habit  which  we  cannot  break  when  we  pass  suddenly 
from  the  train  ^to  the  platform.  Yet  there  is  an  alterna- 
tive explanation!  It  may  be  due  to  a  cause  which  is  purely 
geometrical  and  to  no  change  whatever  in  ourselves.  The 
space  into  which  we  step  may  be  so  altered  in  its  character 
by  the  movement  of  the  train  relatively  to  it,  that  the  direction 
of  things  entering  it  are  automatically  changed.  Again,  to 
take  another  example,  we  are  all  familiar  with  the  popular 


EINSTEIN'S  THEOKY  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  171 

experiment  in  physical  laboratories  to  show  the  behaviour  of 
iron  filings  when  a  magnet  is  brought  into  their  neighbour- 
hood. We  say  that  the  filings  are  magnetised  and  suppose 
that  the  definite  and  ordered  arrangement  they  assume  is 
due  to  a  change  they  have  undergone  under  the  influence 
of  the  magnet.  But  there  is  an  alternative  explanation. 
It  may  be  due  to  the  geometry  of  the  magnetic  field.  It 
may  be  that  the  filings  undergo  no  change  in  their  nature 
whatever  and  that  their  apparent  behaviour  may  be  the 
simple  and  mechanical  effect  of  the  strains  and  tensions  of 
space  in  the  magnetic  field.  According  to  the  generalised 
theory,  this  is  the  scientific  explanation.  The  reason  for 
choosing  these  alternatives  in  each  of  these  cases  is  that  the 
interpretation  of  the  phenomena  they  offer  is  at  once  simpler 
and  intelligible.  Precisely  in  the  same  way  when  Copernicus 
announced  the"  helio-centric  alternative  as  an  interpretation 
of  celestial  phenomena,  it  forced  itself  on  the  acceptance  of 
the  scientific  world  by  its  simplicity  and  intelligibility. 

I  am  quite  ready  to  admit  that  philosophy,  in  its  technical 
meaning,  is  not  necessarily  concerned  with  the  reasons  which 
men  of  science  may  have  for  deciding  between  alternatives 
such  as  these.  But  suppose  a  philosopher  or  a  philosophy  to 
be  committed  to  one  interpretation  of  the  facts,  presupposing 
it  as  the  starting-point  of  theory  and  therefore  excluding  the 
alternative,  there  is  no  possibility  of  indifference  then.  It  is 
not  a  matter  for  the  mathematicians  to  settle,  for  the  philo- 
sophy stands  or  falls  with  the  decision.  This  seems  to  me  to 
be  precisely  the  case  in  which  the  materialists  and  natural 
realists  stand.  They  suppose  they  can  be  indifferent  whereas 
their  whole  philosophical  principle  is  at  stake. 

To  return  for  a  moment  to  our  two  illustrations,  the  alter- 
native interpretations  bring  to  light  two  principles  which 
present  to  one  another  a  complete  contrast.  The  common- 
sense  interpretation  invokes  as  fact,  on  the  basis  of  empirical 
intuition,  a  principle  which  on  the  objective  side  is  both  un- 
intelligible and  irrational — the  principle  of  action  at  a  distance ; 
and  on  the  subjective  side  supposes  occult  changes  in  the 
nature  of  the  agent  which  induce  an  illusion  in  the  action,  in 
itself  quite  inexplicable.  The  other  principle  interprets  the 
behaviour  by  simply  setting  itself  to  discover  the  geometry  of 
the  field  in  which  the  apparent  action  occurs.  From  the 
standpoint  of  pure  methodology  only  the  second  principle  can 
claim  to  be  scientific. 

So  far,  however,  I  have  spoken  of  these  two  alternatives  as 
though  the  choice  were  freely  open  to  us  to  accept  or  reject 
either,  and  as  though,  in  choosing,  the  only  decisive  factors 


172  H.  WILDON  CAKE: 

were  simplicity  and  convenience.  But  science  requires  more 
than  this,  it  wants  assurance  of  fact.  It  must  be  satisfied 
before  everything  that  the  basis  of  reality  on  which  it  builds 
is  absolute.  It  cannot  compromise.  Galileo,  after  his  re- 
cantation, when  the  famous  words  eppur  si  nwove  escaped 
his  lips,  was  instinctively  expressing  the  inmost  nature  of  the 
scientific  spirit.  Einstein  is  his  true  follower.  He  sees  with 
the  clearness  of  intuition  that  the  one  essential  condition  of 
science  is  the  absoluteness  of  its  foundation,  and  his  marvel- 
lous genius  has  directed  him  unerringly  to  the  only  ground 
on  which  that  absoluteness  can  be  established — sense-ex- 
perience. 

I  will  now  explain  what  I  take  to  be  the  special  and  im- 
portant work  of  Einstein  so  far  as  it  affects  philosophy.  It 
seems  to  me  then  that  just  as  Descartes,  probing  the  signi- 
ficance of  the  Copernican  theory  and  forced  thereby  to  his 
method  of  universal  doubt,  discovered  the  fundamental  truth 
that  the  "I  think"  affirms  an  existence  secure  from  doubt, 
so  Einstein,  searching  for  the  significance  of  the  negative 
result  of  the  Michelson-Morley  experiment,  and  convinced  of 
the  impossibility  and  futility  of  presupposing  the  existence 
of  the  absolute  which  science  requires,  in  a  hypothetical 
substratum,  concluded  that  it  must  lie  in  knowledge  itself. 
To  this  conclusion  he  was  no  doubt  directed  by  the  influence 
on  him  of  the  work  of  Ernst  Mach.  He  finds  the  absolute 
precisely  where  Descartes  found  it,  in  the  "  I  think "  of 
active  living  experience,  but  whereas  Descartes  failed  to 
discover  any  way  of  passing  from  the  "  I  think "  to  the 
reality  of  the  physical  world,  and  at  last  fell  back  on  the 
expedient  of  invoking  the  principle  of  the  veracity  of  God, 
Einstein  has  found  a  way  which  at  no  point  whatever  in- 
troduces either  hypothetical  factor  or  transcendent  cause. 
It  is  this,  apart  from  any  special  value  in  his  actual  mathe- 
matical work,  which  constitutes  the  claim  of  his  theory  to  be 
philosophy.  His  scheme  of  a  universal  geometry  is  in  its 
essentials  remarkably  similar  to  Descartes's  universal  mechan- 
ism. It  differs  from  it  in  the  important  particular  that 
whereas  Descartes  conceived  the  universe  as  three-dimen- 
sional, and  its  space  as  Euclidean,  and  independent  of  the 
time-factor,  Einstein  conceives  it  as  four-dimensional  with 
time  as  one  of  the  axes  of  co-ordination,  but  the  superiority 
of  Einstein's  scheme  from  the  standpoint  of  philosophy  is 
that  its  construction  and  constitution  are  inherent  in  and 
never  transcend  the  conditions  of  actual  individual  experience. 

The  principle  of  relativity  is  not  the  rejection  of  an  absolute 
and  the  affirmation  of  universal  relativity.  That  would 


EINSTEIN'S  THEOBY  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  173 

be  equivalent  to  the  affirmation  of  universal  scepticism. 
What  the  principle  rejects  is  an  absolute  which  is  independent 
of  experience,  and  therefore  outside  knowledge,  an  absolute 
which  has  to  be  postulated  as  the  condition  of  knowledge. 
The  absolute  of  the  relativists  is  in  experience  and  there- 
fore wears  a  different  aspect.  The  principle  of  relativity 
claims  that  it  is  workable  and  that  it  provides  a  position 
from  which  advance  can  be  made  and  nature  interpreted. 
It  yields  in  the  first  place  a  mathematics,  and  this  in  its 
turn  can  offer  a  material  to  physics.  It  completely  reverses 
therefore  the  old  order  according  to  which  mathematics  was 
an  abstraction  from  physics.  In  the  new  principle  physics 
depends  on  mathematics  and  not  vice  versa,  and  mathe- 
matics becomes  an  empirical  instead  of  a  transcendental 
science. 

It  was  a  scientific  discovery,  and  a  philosophical  necessity 
arising  from  that  discovery,  which  led  Newton  to  affirm 
absolute  space  and  time.  It  is  because  the  theory  was  based 
upon  and  necessitated  by  a  definite  scientific  fact  that  Newton 
never  regarded  it  as  hypothesis.  The  discovery  was  that 
there  is  a  velocity  of  light.  The  story  of  the  reflection  on 
the  fall  of  the  apple  belongs  to  the  year  1665,  the  Principia 
was  published  in  1686.  It  was  midway  between  these 
two  events,  in  1675,  that  Boemer,  the  Danish  astronomer, 
observed  the  discrepancies  in  the  times  of  Jupiter's  moons, 
which  could  only  be  satisfactorily  explained  by  the  theory 
that  there  is  a  definite  velocity  of  the  propagation  of  light. 
It  was  this  discovery,  previously  neither  suspected  nor 
even  imagined,  which  necessitated  the  postulate  of  absolute 
space  and  time.  It  is  clear  that  without  such  a  postulate  it 
was  no  longer  possible  to  fix  a  time-table  for  astronomical 
events.  The  planetary  movements  do  not  occur  when  they 
are  observed,  their  precise  date  must  be  calculated.  This  is 
why,  in  spite  of  all  philosophical  difficulties  and  theological 
objections,  Newton's  postulate  won  immediate  and  universal 
recognition  in  science.  For  two  centuries  nothing  occurred 
to  throw  doubt  on  it.  But  now  a  scientific  discovery, 
and  a  philosophical  necessity  arising  from  that  discovery, 
has  led  Einstein  to  reject  this  postulate  and  compelled 
him  to  look  elsewhere  than  in  space  or  time,  or  generally  in 
the  external  world  considered  as  independent  existence,  for 
an  absolute  on  which  to  base  the  concept  of  physical  reality. 
Let  us  then  endeavour  to  follow  the  argument  in  so  far  as  a 
principle  of  philosophy  is  involved. 

The  velocity  of  light  must,  as  Newton  saw,  be  included  in 
all  the  equations  which  are  concerned  with  the  measurement 


174  H.    WILDON    CAER  : 

of  celestial  phenomena.  Scientific  discovery  has  now  estab- 
lished as  fact  that  this  velocity,  though  finite,  is  constant  for 
all  observers,  whatever  the  relative  velocity  of  the  systems 
to  which  they  are  attached.  The  postulated  absolute  of 
Newton's  Principia  is  therefore  condemned  as  futile.  The 
reason  is  obvious.  There  can  be  no  experience  of  an  inde- 
pendent system  of  reference  which  would  provide  us  with  the 
means  of  compounding  the  velocity  of  light  with  velocities  of 
translation,  because  light  signals  are  our  ultimate  resource. 
Clearly  all  astronomical  observations,  that  is,  all  knowledge 
of  the  universe  beyond  the  range  of  our  muscular  and  other 
bodily  activities,  depend  on  visual  experience  and  its  inter- 
pretation. Velocity  is  a  ratio  between  two  factors,  space  and 
time.  If  then  a  velocity  is  constant  under  conditions  which 
imply  variation,  the  component  factors  must  vary.  It  follows 
therefore  that  the  absolute  is  not  in  the  object  of  knowledge 
taken  in  abstraction,  that  is,  it  is  not  in  the  external  world, 
it  is  in  the  observer  or  subject  of  knowledge  and  a  function 
of  his  activity.  How  then  is  subjectivism  avoided  and 
physical  science  possible  ?  This  is  the  point  of  supreme 
philosophical  interest. 

The  absolute  is  the  "  I  think  "  which  in  affirming  its  activity 
posits  existence.  The  "  I  think  "  does  not  presuppose  exist- 
ence ;  it  is  not  generated  but  generator.  What  does  it  pos- 
sess wherewith  to  construct,  order,  regulate,  and  constitute 
the  world  which  it  posits  by  the  very  nature  of  its  activity  ? 
Descartes  replied,  extension  and  movement ;  these,  he  said, 
are  clear  and  distinct  ideas  in  our  mind  and  their  existence 
as  an  external  world  is  guaranteed  by  the  veracity  of  God. 
Einstein  replies,  sense-experience ;  this  alone  is  the  immediate 
object  of  consciousness,  and  from  it  therefore  the  physical 
reality  of  science  is  constituted.  What  then  is  the  mode  or 
form  of  the  activity  of  the  "I  think"  which  gives  this 
physical  reality  ?  Einstein  replies,  geometrising.  Sense-ex- 
perience presents  itself  to  consciousness  in  the  form  of  event, 
and  the  fundamental  activity  of  consciousness  consists  in  co- 
ordinating events.  In  this  co-ordinating  we  use  four  axes, 
three  for  space  and  one  for  time,  and  thereby  we  are  able  to 
fix  the  point-instant  of  every  event  in  relation  to  every  other. 
How  does  such  a  process,  being  essentially  individual,  yield  a 
common  objective  universe,  a  universe  of  which  there  can  be 
mathematical  and  physical  science  in  the  absolute  meaning?  It 
is  in  the  answer  to  this  question  that  the  whole  significance  for 
philosophy  of  Einstein's  scientific  revolution  seems  to  me  to  lie. 

The  starting-point  of  the  new  theory  is  the  rejection  out- 
right, not  on  purely  logical  or  epistemological  grounds,  but 


EINSTEIN'S  THEORY  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  175 

as  experimentally  disproved,  of  the  belief  in  a  substratum, 
material  or  spiritual,  mathematical  (space-time)  or  physical 
(matter  or  ether),  hypothetically  postulated  as  the  cause  of 
the  phenomena  of  nature.  The  rejection  of  this  hypothesis 
in  any  form  leaves  us  with  only  one  alternative.  If  the  ab- 
solute is  not  what  we  observe  in  nature,  and  nature  does  not 
supply  us  with  a  standard  of  reference,  then  the  phenomena 
of  nature  must  be  relative  to  a  standard  which  is  furnished 
by  the  observer  himself.  That  we  do  in  fact  furnish  our- 
selves with  a  standard  in  measuring  phenomena  is  entirely 
in  accord  with  experience.  Our  "  I  think  "  is  as  matter  of 
fact  attached  to  a  system  of  reference,  primarily  to  our  body 
as  the  mobile  instrument  of  activity,  secondarily  to  a  particu- 
lar physical  environment  which  provides  and  also  limits  the 
range  of  our  activity.  It  is  from  these  systems  of  reference, 
and  in  relation  to  them,  that  we  derive  our  axes  of  co-ordina- 
tion, and  determine  our  units  of  measurement.  We  find 
therefore  in  ourselves,  in  the  activity  of  consciousness  itself, 
in  the  nature  of  the  "  I  think  "  and  the  necessity  it  imposes 
upon  us  of  organising  our  activity,  both  the  standard  of 
magnitude  and  the  norm  of  direction.  '  When  we  observe 
systems  in  movement,  systems  of  reference  to  which  we  are 
not  attached  and  which  are  moving  uniformly  or  non-uni- 
formly  in  relation  to  our  own,  we  co-ordinate  these,  but 
necessarily  from  the  standpoint  of  our  own  system  at  rest. 
If  this  be  granted  let  us  see  precisely  what  follows  from  it. 
The  principle  declares,  we  repeat,  that  an  observer  attached 
to  a  system  of  reference,  co-ordinates  every  point-instant  of 
an  event,  and  the  world-line,  that  is,  the  track  of  such  an 
event  in  the  four-dimensional  universe  of  his  sense-experience, 
not  from  the  standpoint  of  an  independent  absolute  system, 
but  from  the  fixity  or  stability  of  his  own  system  regarded  as 
at  rest.  It  follows  then  that  if  the  observer's  system  itself 
changes  relatively  to  other  systems  such  change  will  appear 
as  change  in  the  other  systems.  Also  if  the  observer  pass 
suddenly  from  one  system  of  reference  to  another,  which  may 
even  reverse  all  the  conditions  of  the  first,  he  will  carry  with 
him  the  standard  and  norm,  and  these  will  automatically 
adjust  themselves,  so  that  every  system  into  which  he  passes 
will  by  the  very  condition  of  his  attachment  to  it  be  a  system 
at  rest.  All  this  the  principle  itself  explicitly  lays  down. 
We  have  then  only  to  extend  it  by  the  recognition  that  to 
every  observer  attached  to  a  system  moving  in  relation  to 
ours,  his  system  is  for  him  at  rest  and  ours  to  him  is  moving, 
and  his  axes  of  co-ordination  must  then  vary  in  relation 
to  ours  according  to  the  velocity  and  uniformity  of  his 


176  H.    WILDON   CAKE: 

movement  relatively  to  ours.  There  is  no  limit  to  this  principle 
theoretically.  There  is  a  geometry  therefore  of  every  point- 
instant  in  the  universe  because  we  can  conceive  it  as  a  system 
of  reference  from  which  some  observer  is  co-ordinating  events. 
No  point  and  no  instant  can  have  relations  to  other  points 
and  other  instants  which  are  identical  for  observers  in  differ- 
ent systems.  Is  such  an  infinite  plurality  and  absolute  sub- 
jectivity consistent  with  the  community  of  basis  which  science 
demands  for  its  reality  ? 

A  very  simple  illustration  from  ordinary  experience  may 
serve  to  indicate  the  nature  of  the  reply  to  this  question. 
What  do  we  mean  when  we  speak  of  pain  ?  We  all  know 
what  it  is,  and  we  distinguish  it  into  kinds  according  to  the 
definite  conditions  under  which  it  occurs,  and  not  according 
to  the  individuality  of  the  persons  who  experience  it.  We 
conceive  pain  as  identical  though  the  subjects  who  experience 
it  are  diverse.  In  what  then  does  this  identity  consist? 
Clearly  not  in  sameness  for  there  is  no  sameness.  What  one 
individual  experiences  cannot  be  experienced  by  another. 
Identity  consists  simply  in  the  fact  that  we  can  establish 
point-to-point  correspondences  between  individuals.  No  one 
imagines  that  to  establish  identity  there  must  be  assumed  to 
exist  an  independent  pain-in-itself  which  no  one  suffers  but 
which  is  the  transcendental  cause  when  anyone  suffers. 
Einstein  holds  that  precisely  the  same  principle  applies  to  the 
co-ordination  of  events  and  to  scientific  reality  in  general. 
There  is  no  unco-ordinated  event,  no  absolute  event  in  an  in- 
dependent system,  and  there  is  no  sameness  of  events  occur- 
ring to  different  observers.  In  order  that  there  shall  be 
identical  events  for  observers  in  different  systems,  all  that  is 
necessary  is  that  the  axes  of  co-ordination  of  any  system 
shall  correspond  with  those  of  another  and  therefore  be  trans- 
formable one  into  another.  Observers  in  different  systems 
will  then  describe  the  observed  event  in  the  same  terms,  the 
facts  will  be  common  to  all,  and  the  laws  of  nature  will  be 
universal. 

The  whole  conception  of  the  universe  is  now  seen  to  be  the 
exact  reverse  of  that  on  which  materialists  and  natural 
realists  have  insisted.  Instead  of  a  limited  knowledge  of  an 
infinite  universe,  the  new  principle  gives  us  a  universe  the 
knowledge  of  which  is  unbounded  but  the  reality  of  which  is 
finite.  The  two  essential  conditions  on  which  the  material- 
istic conception  depended,  simultaneity  and  direction,  condi- 
tions of  the  possibility  of  dating  every  event  and  fixing  every 
point,  have  been  falsified  by  experiment.  The  new  concep- 
tion is  not  the  arbitrary  speculation  of  a  fertile  imagination, 


EINSTEIN'S  THEORY  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  177 

it  is  imposed  on  thought  by  an  inherent  necessity  of  its 
nature.  The  physical  universe  is  the  systematisation  of 
infinite  space-time  systems,  on  a  principle  which  only  asks  us 
never  to  loosen  our  hold  on  experience  in  order  to  go  beneath 
or  beyond  it,  but  always  and  only  to  seek  to  interpret  it. 

Einstein's  conclusion  that  the  physical  universe  is  finite 
but  unbounded  follows  necessarily  from  the  principle  that 
the  absolute  is  the  "I  think"  of  personal  experience  and 
from  the  fact  that  the  nature  of  its  activity  is  geometrising. 
The  universe  is  finite  because  the  straight  line  of  every 
observer  is  curved  for  other  observers,  and  therefore  every 
straight  line  is  a  geodesic  which  at  infinity  must  return  on 
itself ;  and  the  universe  is  unbounded  because  the  approach 
to  the  limit  is  infinite. 

I  will  carry  this  argument  no  further,  not  because  I  am. 
likely  to  have  said  enough  to  silence  criticism,  but  because  to 
interpret  the  full  significance  of  the  argument  for  this  con- 
ception of  a  finite  yet  unbounded  universe  would  involve  the 
history  of  the  mathematical  researches  of  Gauss  andBiemann, 
and  the  physical  researches  of  Faraday,  Clerk  Maxwell,  and 
their  successors,  a  task  I  am  not  competent  to  undertake. 
My  argument  is  addressed  ,to  my  fellow-philosophers.  I  am 
amazed  at  what  seems  to  me  their  short-sightedness  in 
imagining  that  philosophy  can  be  indifferent  to  this  stupen- 
dous revolution  in  science. 


12 


V.— DISCUSSIONS. 
"THIS  OR  NOTHING." 

I  SHOULD  like  to  make  my  position  clear,  if  I  can,  on  two  principal 
points  of  the  logical  doctrine  asserted  in  my  book  Implication  and 
Linear  Inference.  Such  explanations  would  have  been  better  in 
place,  perhaps,  in  a  second  edition,  rather  than  in  MIND  at  an 
interval  of  two  years  after  Prof.  Broad's  very  courteous  review.1 
But  an  opportunity  of  the  former  kind  does  not  always  occur. 

I  can  best  introduce  my  explanations  if  I  refer  here  and 
there  to  the  review  in  question.  But  my  hope  is  that  what  I  say 
may  be  enough  of  a  positive  development  to  have  an  interest  for 
its  own  sake,  and  not  to  be  regarded  in  a  controversial  light. 

The  two  points  I  wish  to  speak  of  are  (1)  My  attitude  towards 
accepting  laws  of  logic  or  axioms  of  science  separately  and  each  on 
its  own  merits,  and  (2)  The  possibility,  on  the  principle  I  advocate, 
of  admitting  that  there  exists  a  legitimate  Induction,  such  as 
establishes  general  laws  which  can  be  "  borrowed  "  and  "  applied," 
distinct  from  the  "linear"  inference  against  which  my  main 
argument,  in  the  work  on  Implication,  is  directed. 

It  appears  to  me  to-day  that  one  preliminary  word  is  needed  to 
justify  the  negative  approach  to  my  principle  indicated  in  the 
phrase  "this  or  nothing".  Why  not,  "this  because  of  every- 
thing"? The  principle  seems  naturally  to  frame  itself  in  the 
former  shape.  And  I  suppose  the  reason  is  that  denying  a  pro- 
position may  force  us  to  deny  many  propositions  which  are  not 
necessary  to  prove  it.  And,  therefore,  by  examining  how  much 
we  must  affirm  in  the  antecedent  in  order  to  establish  the  conse- 
quent, we  could  not  exhibit  the  connexion  of  the  two  as  completely 
as  by  enquiring  how  much  we  must  deny  if  we  deny  the  conse- 
quent. 

(1)  Thus  it  would  seem  that  at  any  rate  we  lose  nothing  by 
starting  from  the  denial  of  the  consequent.  It  experiments  with 
the  truth  the  condition  of  whose  validity  is  to  be  considered,  and 
raises  a  direct  discussion  of  what  that  condition  is. 

The  form  of  argument  which  I  am  going  to  adopt  in  carrying 
out  this  procedure,  is  not,  I  think,  the  only  form  conceivable ;  but 
I  prefer  it  as  representing,  in  my  belief,  the  normal  path  of  our 
thought,  although  it  involves,  I  think,  a  paradox  which  I  have 
not  seen  noted  before. 

1MiND,  July,  1920. 


BEKNARD  BOSANQUET :    "THIS   OR  NOTHING".  179 

Thus,  instead  of  at  once  pronouncing  that  we  must  violate  one 
of  the  laws  of  logic,  the  law  of  antecedent  and  consequent,  if  we 
elect,  on  denying  the  consequent,  to  maintain  the  affirmation  of 
the  antecedent ;  we  would  rather  try  the  experiment  of  relying  on 
those  laws  to  the  bitter  end,  and  noting  the  result  to  our  knowledge 
and  to  themselves. 

In  this  form  of  argument  then,  I  should  not  refuse  to  draw  the 
normal  inference  from  the  denial  of  a  consequent  to  the  denial  of 
its  acknowledged  antecedent.  The  denial  of  the  consequent  is 
here  postulated  to  be  unreasonable,  but  we  accept  it  ad  hoc,  and 
ask  where  it  leads  us.  It  leads  us,  of  course,  through  the  denial 
of  the  first  antecedent  to  the  denial  of  the  whole  series  of  ante- 
cedents in  which  each  in  turn  is  a  consequent.  And  this  result 
must  necessarily  expand,  and  infect  ultimately  the  entire  connected 
system  on  the  basis  of  which  the  truth  originally  denied  is  taken 
as  established.  Every  such  system  possesses  connexions  which 
link  each  individual  truth  with  an  ample  system  of  confirmatory 
truths,  and  as  these  successively  come  to  be  denied  the  disease 
must  spread  deeper  into  the  roots  of  the  reality  we  believe  in,  and 
therefore  also  more  widely  over  other  superficial  truths  which 
share  these  roots  with  the  truth  first  denied. 

I  will  not  occupy  space  by  drawing  out  an  example,  which  is 
easily  done,  but  will  merely  say  what  I  have  in  mind  as  a  very 
obvious  case,  and  that  is  that  the  ungrounded  denial  (this  of  course 
is  the  point ;  a  grounded  denial  would  merely  set  up  the  ordinary 
process  by  which  experience  corrects  our  knowledge)  of,  say,  a 
historical  truth,  would  bring  us  in  a  very  few  steps  to  the  denial 
that  sense-perception  has  any  validity  at  all  (not  merely  the  denial 
of  any  special  theory  of  its  modus  operandi).  And  along  with  this 
would  go  the  reliability  of  historical  canons,  and  of  human  testi- 
mony and  communication  in  toto.  How  far  our  doctrine  of  space 
and  time  would  survive  the  repudiation  of  sense-perception  it  is 
beyond  me  to  say.  But  I  should  have  thought  the  world  of  our 
experience  would  be  pretty  well  reduced  to  chaos  by  such  a  train 
of  argument,  which  might  be  extended,  I  really  think,  at  pleasure. 
With  any  scientific  truth  such  an  argument  would  be  much  more 
effective. 

But  of  course,  as  the  reader  sees  at  once,  in  this  argument  we 
have  implied  an  extraordinary  paradox.  We  have  not  prima  facie 
contradicted  the  laws  of  logic,  but  on  the  contrary  we  have  so  far 
got  a  lot  of  work  out  of  them,  using  them  to  demolish  the  accepted 
structure  of  our  world. 

Nevertheless,  at  the  bitter  end,  it  seems  to  me  that  we  do  get 
the  surprising  situation  that  in  virtue  of  the  laws  of  logic  we  are 
driven  (supposing  the  complete  success  in  principle  of  this  negative 
argument)  to  try  to  assert,  what  has  to  begin  with  a  perfectly 
definite  meaning,  "  No  propositions  are  true  ".  Such  a  proposition 
claims  of  course  to  deny  both  itself  and  the  laws  of  logic,  which  so 
far  we  have  not  denied,  but  have  relied  on. 


180  BEBNAKD  BOSANQUET  I 

There  is  a  doctrine  (Broad,  MIND,  115,  p.  327)  according  to  which 
this  form  of  words  "  Nothing  is  true  "  is  meaningless,  and  so  is  not 
a  proposition.  I  am  not  able  to  estimate  that  doctrine,  but  the 
suggestion  is  helpful.  I  accept  it,  and  interpret  it  thus. 

The  proposition  in  question  is  certainly  in  one  aspect  meaning- 
less. Every  negation  contains  a  failure  to  think.  Every  negation 
rests  on  a  privation.  At  the  actual  point  where  exclusion  or 
collision  should  be  present  the  terms  do  not  quite  come  together. 
There  is  a  gap.  We  "do  not  see,"  we  "  cannot  understand,"  we 
"cannot  think"  how  the  proposition  can  be  thought;  how  its 
terms  can  be  brought  into  union.  "No  square  is  round"  ;  that  is, 
we  do  not  see  how  round  and  square  can  be  thought  as  one.  Now 
our  proposition  "  Nothing  is  true "  is  the  limiting  case  of  this 
failure.  In  face  of  our  postulated  denial  of  an  unimpeachable 
truth,  we  "do  not  understand,"  we  "cannot  think,"  how  any 
proposition  can  be  true.  The  meaninglessness,  or  failure  to 
achieve  a  thought,  characteristic  of  negation,  is  here  extended  to 
the  union  of  the  terms,  say,  "  proposition "  and  "  truth ".  A 
proposition  to  this  effect  is  certainly,  on  one  side,  meaningless. 
But  yet  again  we  know  what  it  means,  as  we  know  what  is  meant 
by  a  square  not  being  round.  We  know  what  a  proposition  is 
and  what  truth  is,  and  so  we  know  what  we  are  attempting  when 
we  try  to  think  them  in  one,  and,  because  of  a  certain  condition, 
fail.  Thus  the  proposition  is  meaningless,  as  the  limiting  case  of 
negation.  It  is  a  failure  to  think,  as  conveying  a  contradiction ; 
but  it  is  not  unintelligible. 

Now  in  being  brought  to  attempt  to  assert  it,  we  have  been 
brought  to  attempt  to  deny  the  laws  of  logic ;  for  they  are  propo- 
sitions and  we  are  to  deny  all  propositions.  How  is  it  conceivable 
that  we  should  deny  them,  when  we  have  assumed  them  through- 
out our  argument?  And  how  are  we  to  state  the  reason,  for 
which,  nevertheless,  we  find  it  impossible  to  deny  them  ? 

It  would  be  a  paradox,  but  it  would  illustrate  my  view  very 
suggestively,  to  say  that  we  deny  them,  under  the  supposed  con- 
dition, because  it  forbids  us  to  make  a  proposition ;  and  not  that 
we  are  unable  to  make  a  proposition  because  we  are  denying  the 
laws  of  logic. 

For  I  do  not  think  that  the  view  which  says  that  we  accept 
them,  and  other  truths  which  seem  to  have  the  same  kind  of 
evidence,  severally  each  on  its  own  merits,  and  the  view  which  I 
express  as  "  This  or  nothing,"  are  really  so  much  in  conflict  as 
might  appear.  What  I  should  say  here  is  that  the  fundamental 
fact  is  the  spirit  of  self-development  in  thought,  revealed  by  the 
ideal  experiment  made  in  actual  thinking.  Thought  will  go  for- 
ward if  it  possibly  can.  It  will  affirm  meanings ;  and  order  or 
connexion  which  is  one  side  of  meaning.  This  might  be  called  a 
non-formal  principle.1  The  laws  of  logic  and  other  axioms  are 
merely,  I  suggest,  the  expression  of  our  elementary  experiments  in 

1  Gf.  Bradley,  Principles  of  Logic,  p.  451. 


"THIS  OE  NOTHING".  181 

actual  thinking  at  different  points  of  our  experience.  Each,  there- 
fore, is  certainly  necessary  on  its  own  merits.  Thought,  experi- 
menting at  the  point  concerned,  will  make  its  advance,  and  will 
not  be  denied.  But  this  is  only  because  thought  cannot  help  doing 
its  work  of  synthesis  and  analysis,  effecting  any  advance  to  which 
they  point  the  way ;  and  all  the  laws  and  axioms  are  just  initial 
conditions  of  its  orderly  connexions,  consisting  in  pervading  con- 
nexions of  the  same  kind. 

And,  as  I  suggested,  if  thought  is  stopped  from  experimenting, 
i.e.,  from  thinking,  then  it  has  no  means  of  displaying  its  necessity. 
Here  zs  actually  our  ultimate  contradiction.  If  we  are  not  allowed 
to  think,  we  are  not  allowed  to  exercise  the  act  which  these  per- 
vading laws  need  for  their  establishment.  They  are  not  premises. 
They  are  principles  evident  throughout  our  thinking  as  the 
manners  of  its  self-assertion.  The  principle  of  Disjunction  does 
not  depend  on  the  Law  of  Excluded  Middle.  The  "law"  is  a 
case  of  the  principle,  which  you  can  see  at  work  in  any  disjunction. 
It  is  a  consequence  of  using  the  negative  as  an  absolute  alternative, 
which  is  a  necessity  of  the  method  by  which  thought  proceeds. 
But  if  thought  is  forbidden  to  proceed,  the  principle  cannot  be 
established. 

This  is  not  a  "  psychological "  necessity.  It  is  a  necessity  of  the 
nature  of  reality  which  it  is  thought's  function  and  character  to  reveal. 
How  do  we  know  it  is  thought's  function  and  character  to  do  so  ? 
Because  every  act  of  thought  says  so.  Thought,  in  asserting,  does 
not  say  "  I  think  so  ".  It  says  "  it  is  so  ".  "  I  think  so  "  is  merely 
one  case  of  "it  is  so,"  and  is  as  absolute  as  any  other  assertion  of 
a  fact  about  reality. 

Thus  in  my  view  the  Laws  of  Logic  and  other  truths  having 
apparently  the  same  kind  of  certainty,  are,  certainly,  severally 
necessary  on  their  own  merits,  because  they  are  established  by  ideal 
experiment  as  essential  to  the  working  of  thought  in  affirming  the 
systematic  nature  of  reality.  You  can  therefore  actually  use  them, 
where  a  barrier  is  set  up  against  thought,  to  exhibit  the  demolition 
of  experience  which  results,  and  yet  this  demolition,  as  annulling 
the  process  in  which  alone  they  can  be  displayed,  ultimately  must 
bring  them  into  contradiction  with  themselves.  You  can  grasp  the 
Law  of  Identity  if  you  can  make  a  proposition.  But  suppose  you 
have  estopped  yourself  from  framing  a  proposition  ? 

Of  course  in  a  sense  the  whole  argument  is  ideal  and  imaginary. 
In  fact,  thought  will  not  give  way,  and  refuses  to  enter  into  the 
intolerable  situation  depicted,  in  which  it  at  once  must,  and  cannot, 
fulfil  its  own  nature.  But  that  is  why  it  cannot  and  will  not  deny 
an  unimpeachable  truth,  deny,  that  is,  without  a  special  suspicion 
at  some  point.  If  it  did,  it  would  annihilate  its  world. 

(2)  I  want  to  point  out  that  I  fully  recognise  a  kind  of  inference, 
which  may  be  called  Induction,  which  works  with  borrowed 
premises  and  to  some  extent  with  the  substitution  of  particulars 
for  generals.  But  I  believe  that  my  principle  will  explain  and 


182  BEENABD   BOSANQUET  I 

justify  this  kind  of  inference  in  the  only  way  which  is  logically 
sound. 

Here  the  way  is  more  than  half  cleared  for  me  by  Prof.  Broad, 
and  I  have  only  to  show  that  I  can  avail  myself  of  his  distinction  on 
my  principle.  I  quote  from  MIND,  115,  p.  335  :  "  Thus  the  function 
of  substituting  constants  for  variables  is  quite  different  in  the  two 
cases.  In  the  argument  about  the  moon's  motion  it  is  a  step 
that  actually  has  to  be  performed  in  the  course  of  the  proof  if 
the  conclusion  is  to  be  reached.  In  the  syllogism  about  Socrates 
it  is  not  a  step  in  the  proof,  but  an  additional  statement,  which 
may  or  may  not  be  made,  about  the  proof,"  and  page  337  :  "  There 
is  a  genuine  connexion  between  the  induction  that  only  argues  by 
analogy  and  the  linear  inference  that  can  only  use  syllogism. 
The  connexion  is  that  induction  which  only  proceeds  by  likeness 
and  difference  can  at  most  establish  laws  of  the  mere  conjunction 
and  disjunction  of  attributes,  and  no  use  can  be  made  of  such 
laws  except  as  majors  for  syllogisms.  But  there  are  other  kinds 
of  law,  and  these  are  reached  by  another  kind  of  induction,  and 
can  be  used  as  premises  for  another  kind  of  deduction."  Com- 
pare Green,  Works,  II.,  288  :  "  From  the  connexion  of  any  set  of 
phenomena  as  merely  resembling,  no  science  results ;  once  connect 
them  as  constituents  of  a  quantity,  and  we  have  the  beginnings  of 
science  ". 

I  have  to  show  how  I  recognise,  and  explain  on  my  principle, 
the  sort  of  Induction  indicated  in  the  last  sentence  quoted  from 
Prof.  Broad. 

Of  course  I  see  that  general  laws  are  "  established,"  "  borrowed," 
and  "  applied,"  in  science.  The  question  is  as  to  the  nature  of  the 
laws  and  in  what  sense  they  are  "  borrowed  ".  This  seems  to  me 
to  be  excellently  stated  in  the  passages  from  Profs.  Broad  and 
Green.  As  I  understand,  the  scientific  law  represents  a  certain 
stage  in  a  process  of  intellectual  work,  an  analytic  synthesis  or  syn- 
thetic analysis  of  a  certain  province  of  phenomena,  which  embodies 
the  connexion  between  the  variations  of  their  factors  in  what  is 
called  a  law.  The  warrant  of  the  law  is,  surely,  simply  that  it  "saves 
the  appearances,"  in  harmony,  of  course,  with  any  further  scientific 
principles  which  are  relevant  to  the  problem.  It  is  itself  an  insight 
won  by  analysing  the  phenomena  as  an  interdependent  system,  and 
it  is  accepted  because  it  is  the  only  way,  or  the  most  successful 
way,  of  ordering  those  phenomena.  Of  course  I  know  that  in  this 
"  success"  there  is  much  that  is  relative,  and  it  is  even  denied  to 
be  capable  of  being  absolute.  I  only  say  that  if  you  take  your  law 
as  true  you  take  it  on  this  principle. 

Now  when  such  a  law  is  "  borrowed  "  and  "  applied  "  of  course 
I  see  that  the  mind  which  applies  it  does  not  unite  the  whole 
analytic-synthetic  insight  and  survey  in  which  it  originated  with 
the  particulars  of  the  case  with  which  he  is  occupied.  But  am  I 
wrong  in  saying  that  he  takes  it  up,  as  a  basis  demanding  in  itself 
an  analytic  or  synthetic  intellectual  apprehension,  and  further  par- 


183 

ticularised  by  a  continuation  of  the  same  analytic-synthetic  move- 
ment by  which  it  was  formed  ?  The  movement  surely  is  the  same, 
and  the  criterion  is  the  same.  The  theory  is  to  be  what  you  must 
have  if  you  are  going  to  "  save  the  appearances".  It  must  stand, 
or  the  appearances  and  confirmatory  principles  must  go.  We  must 
remember  that  as  I  said  above  we  are  putting  an  ideal  case,  that  of 
denying  without  a  ground.  In  practice,  I  presume,  you  only  deny 
upon  a  positive  ground,  and  only  assert  the  principle  so  far  as  to 
remove  the  special  ground  of  your  denial.  That  implies  our 
criterion,  but  does  not  let  it  take  its  ultimate  form.  This  is  surely 
because,  where  the  ultimate  form  could  apply,  no  one  ever  thinks 
of  denying. 

The  borrowed  premise  of  science,  then,  does  not  exclude  a  pro- 
cedure of  extending  insight  into  necessary  relation  within  a  system 
when  it  comes  to  be  applied.  No  insight,  I  think,  can  ever  be 
strictly  particular ;  its  universality  follows  that  of  the  conditions. 
And  surely  I  am  justified  in  insisting  on  it  as  a  fact  that  this  insight 
varies  enormously  in  degree.  This  is  both  really  in  favour  of  my 
view,  and  superficially  against  it.  It  is  really  for  it,  because  it 
recognises  the  insight  or  systematic  apprehension  on  which  I 
insist,  as  an  essential  feature  in  the  application  of  scientific  prin- 
ciple, which  always  figures  in  the  work  of  application,  and  may 
extend  into  the  structure  of  the  principle  itself,  with  very  great 
advantage.  It  is  superficially  against  it,  because,  where  the  insight 
falls  very  low,  the  process  takes  on  almost  the  appearance  of  in- 
ference from  mere  resemblance.  I  am  quite  aware  of  this  point 
and  have  often  insisted  on  it.1  Take  the  case  of  the  schoolboy's 
rule  of  thumb  for  the  rule  of  three.  "Multiply  the  second  and 
third  together  and  divide  by  the  first."  If  only  he  knew  which 
should  be  the  second  and  third,  and  which  should  be  the  first !  If  he 
had  a  slight  insight  into  the  nature  of  proportion,  I  suppose  he  would 
know  this.  But  at  least  he  has  suggested  to  him  the  formula  of  an 
analysis  of  the  problem.  I  submit  that  whenever  the  law  represents 
not  a  repetition  of  conjunctions  but  a  connexion  of  differents,  both 
it  and  its  application  depend  on  the  principle  of  insight  into  in- 
trinsic connexions,  which  of  course  may  be  to  any  extent  mediated 
by  processes  of  analysis  and  synthesis  which  are  the  self-develop- 
ment of  thought.  And  when  this  is  so,  and  consequently  the 
method  employed  in  framing  the  law  has  been  something  analogous 
to  that  of  concomitant  variations,2  I  think  the  distinction  from  in- 
ferences resting  on  resemblances  remains  clear,  even  where  the  law  is 
used  pretty  nearly  as  a  rule  of  thumb,  i.e.,  is  almost  simply 
"  borrowed  "  and  "  applied  ". 

I  cannot  believe  that  even  in  the  more  empirical  sciences  this 
distinction  can  be  explained  away,  and  simple  enumeration  re- 
established as  the  root  of  these  sciences,  as  Mill  made  it  the  root  of 
all.  The  inherent  method  of  thought' seems  to  me  to  forbid  it,  and 

1  See  analysis  of  the  use  of  the  vernier,  Knowledge  and  Reality,  p.  317ff. 

2  Cf.  MIND,  115,  p.  337,  and  Green,  Works,  II.,  285  n.,  quoting  Deschanel. 


184  BEENAED  BOSANQUET  :    "THIS   OE   NOTHING  ". 

to  show  the  features  which  exclude  it  to  be  universal.  "  To  ask 
whether  A  is  really  A,  is1  to  ask  whether  A  is  related  to  other 
possible  experiences  B,  C,  as  I  suppose  it  to  be."  "  One  cannot 
in  strictness  speak  of  testing  a  thing  by  itself."2  "  Every  question 
I  ask  about  the  experience  A  expects  for  its  answer  other  experiences 
B,  C,  D."  3  All  the  laws  of  thought,  it  seems  to  us,  are  exempli- 
fications of  this  character,  and  thought  cannot  work  otherwise. 
"But  in  linear  Induction  it  does  work  otherwise."  I  think  not. 
The  true  uses  of  repetition  in  Induction  have  often  been  explained,4 
and  it  is  not  necessary  to  return  to  them  here. 

1  My  italics.  2Nettleship,  Lectures  on  Logic,  p.  181. 

3  Ibid.,  p.  182.  4  See  e.g.,  my  Logic,  ii.,  p.  135. 

BERNARD  BOSANQUET. 


THE  MEANING  OF  <  SELF  '. 

THESE  observations  on  Dr.  Strong's  Discussion  in  the  January 
Number  do  not  spring,  assuredly,  from  any  desire  contentiously 
to  prolong  a  somewhat  involved  controversy.  But  he  has  made 
it  so  plain  that  he  still  thinks  that  the  Self  is  caught  in  the  dilemma 
that  it  must  be  either  an  object  (or  a  congeries  of  objects)  or 
nothing  at  all,  and  he  is  still  so  unwilling  to  entertain  any  al- 
ternative which  would  extricate  the  Self  that  I  will  make  one  more 
appeal  to  philosophers  to  reconsider  the  method  which  conducts  to 
this  dilemma.  For  I  know  that  Dr.  Strong's  attitude  is  not  peculiar 
to  himself.  It  is  exhibited,  even  more  decidedly,  by  Mr.  Russell's 
Analysis  of  Mind,  and  although  Hume  and  Mill  confessed  the 
bankruptcy  of  sensationalism  on  this  point  long  ago,  the  situation 
apparently  distresses  Mr.  Russell  as  little  as  Dr.  Strong.  Yet  it 
ought  not  to  be  impossible  to  convince  them  that  their  psychological 
method,  plausible  as  it  is  in  many  respects,  definitely  breaks  down 
over  the  crucial  instance  of  the  Self. 

Before,  however,  endeavouring  to  show  that  this  '  analysis/  after 
professing  to  dispense  with  the  Self,  continually  reintroduces  it, 
I  must  guard  myself  against  an  assumption  which  not  only  preju- 
dices Dr.  Strong  against  all  I  can  say  but  blinds  him  to  the  defects 
of  his  own  theory.  The  assumption  is  that  there  are  only  two 
conceivable  alternatives,  so  that  whatever  proves  the  one  untenable 
ipso  facto  establishes  the  other.  The  soul  is  either  a  product  of 
*  sensations,'  or  a  metaphysical  '  substance  '.  Now  this  is  neither 
what  I  believe,  nor  what  I  believe  to  be  true.  Accordingly,  when 
Dr.  Strong  thinks  that  after  rejecting  his  account  there  is  nothing 
open  to  me  but  a  relapse  into  a  '  spiritualistic '  psychology  with 
the  old  metaphysical  notion  of  the  self  as  a  simple  soul-substance, 
and  that  therefore  I  must  be  trying  to  make  '  consciousness '  into 
"  a  pigment  or  menstruum  "  and  "  be  drifting  back  from  the  strictly 
empirical  psychology  of  James  to  something  like  a  spiritualistic 
psychology"  (p.  69)  an  emphatic  protest  is  in  order.  I  have  never 
believed  in  '  consciousness '  in  the  sense  condemned  by  James,  and 
have  never  held  it  to  be  more  than  an  abstraction,  or  piece  of 
philosophic  jargon,  devised  to  conceal  the  personal  character  of 
psychic  facts  by  those  who  had  not  the  courage  to  confess  it.  I 
hold,  on  the  contrary,  that  there  is  no  such  thing  as  consciousness. 
The  category  of  l  thing '  does  not  apply  to  the  living.  But  there 
are  persons,  and  conscious  persons,  and  it  is  worth  considering 
whether  these  are  not  a  better  clue  than  '  things  '  to  the  '  essence  ' 
of  reality.  The  old  metaphysical  soul,  therefore,  being  a  '  thing ' — 


186  F.  c.  s.  SCHILLEB: 

and  a  futile  thing  to  boot — is  quite  as  objectionable  in  psychology  as 
any  concretion  of  '  sense-data  '.  And  I  object  to  it  no  less,  and  for 
the  same  reason,  namely,  that  it  too  cannot  be  a  self  (such  as  we 
all  are),  and  it  too  is  incapable  of  doing  what  every  self  habitually 
and  continually  does.  Neither  the  one  nor  the  other  can  both 
contain,  and  '  own,'  and  be,  its  personal  experiences.  This  inca- 
pacity I  trace  to  a  common  root  in  the  psychological  method  which 
insists  on  treating  the  Self  as  if  it  were  an  '  object '  for  an  (external) 
observer.  This  treatment  seems  to  be  a  manifest  fiction  ;  but  this 
would  not  discredit  it  if  it  were  not  plain  that  in  this  case  it  breaks 
down.  That  it  does  break  down  is  what  I  wish  to  impress  on 
Dr.  Strong  and  Mr.  Eussell.  I  am  less  concerned  to  show  that 
there  is  an  alternative  to  the  psychological  method  which  breaks 
down ;  but  if  Dr.  Strong  is  willing  to  envisage  this  alternative,  it 
is  clear  that  he  will  have  most  carefully  to  beware  of  treating  the 
Self  as  an  *  object '  or  a  compositum  of  '  sense-data,'  and  that  if  he 
will  look  for  such  things,  with  this  method,  he  will  find  them  as 
little  as  he  found  '  activities '  and  '  acts '  with  his  present  method. 

It  may  now  be  possible  to  illustrate  the  contention  that  Dr. 
Strong's  analysis  of  the  Self  is  not  adequate,  after  disposing  of  a 
mutual  misunderstanding.  It  appears  from  the  opening  paragraph 
of  Dr.  Strong's  paper  that  the  '  Self '  equated  with  a  '  rush  of  blood 
and  tension  in  the  head '  was  not  his.  Nor,  certainly,  is  it  mine. 
It  was  merely  his  notion  of  what  my  '  self '  must  be,  on  the  as- 
sumption that  he  had  understood  it.  But  as  this  was  not  the  case, 
it  had  better  be  dropped  by  common  consent. 

Dr.  Strong's  authentic  'self  is,  it  seems,  "all  experience  de- 
objectified".  What  this  means,  and  how  it  happens,  is  not  quite 
easy  to  grasp ;  but  it  is  clear  that  as  '  de-objectify '  is  a  transitive 
verb  we  ought  to  be  informed  who  does  the  'de-objectifying'. 
The  process,  however,  seems  to  start  from  "  a  sensuous  state  used 
as  the  sign  of  an  object "  which  "  conveys  the  object  only  in  the 
form  of  a  '  meaning '  and  does  so  because  we  adopt  the  motor 
attitude  appropriate  to  the  object".  Again  we  note  that  '  we r 
is  the  plural  of  '  I '  ;  but  we  are  not  told  who  '  uses '  the  sensuous 
state,  and  who  are  the  *  we '  that  '  adopt '  the  attitude ;  but  the 
whole  description  seems  to  savour  of  personal  activity  and  to  imply 
the  'self  which  is  being  explained  away. 

We  next  learn  that  the  starting-point  of  this  explanation,  the 
1  sensuous  state,'  is  not  a  fact  of  experience  but  a  figment  of  ex  post 
facto  theorising.  For  "  at  the  moment  of  perception,  being  intent 
on  this  meaning,  we  cannot  be  aware  of  the  sensuous  state". 
Again  who  are  '  we  '  ?  And  does  not  '  intent '  connote  activity  ? 

Though,  however,  we  can  never  directly  be  aware  of  the  '  sensuous 
state,'  we  can  infer  it.  "  That  it  existed  at  that  moment  we  learn 
in  retrospection,  when  we  consider  that  the  meaning  was  brought 
before  us  only  by  the  sensuous  state  used  as  a  sign  "  ;  and  so  "  the 
apparent  existence  of  the  object  was  really  the  existence  of  the 
sensuous  state  or  '  I '  ". 


THE   MEANING   OF    '  SELF  '.  187 

Thus  we  are  asked  to  believe  that  what  at  the  moment  of  ex- 
perience seemed  an  '  object '  turns  out  to  be,  in  retrospect,  the 
very  'self.  Dr.  Strong's  inference  has  certainly  transformed  it 
strangely ;  but  questions  may  arise  both  about  the  adequacy  of  the 
description  and  about  the  validity  of  the  inference.  The  description 
seems  inadequate  because  in  '  the  moment  of  perception  '  also  there 
seemed  to  be  a  '  self '  actively  appropriating  the  '  objects '  it  intends, 
and  this  self  at  least  can  hardly  have  been  one  of  the  objects  it  is 
charged  in  retrospect  with  appropriating  and  converting  to  its  own 
'  uses '.  Moreover,  in  retrospecting  also,  there  still  seems  to  be  a 
'  self '  at  work  (the  same  or  another  ?),  and  it  is  this  that  generates 
the  paradoxical  (and  possibly  mistaken)  doctrine  of  the  '  I '  that 
ever  knows  and  is  never  known.  Thus  at  both  moments  there  is 
found  to  be  a  '  self '  that  is  not  accounted  for  by  Dr.  Strong. 

But  even  if  we  do  not  cavil  at  the  description,  need  we  pass  the 
inference?  If  "the  apparent  existence  of  the  object  was  really 
the  existence  of  the  'I',"  is  not  the  reality  of  'objects'  radically 
impugned  by  our  mature  reflexion  ?  Ought  we  not  to  infer  that 
the  '  I '  creates  the  *  object '  ? 

If  Dr.  Strong  would  draw  this  inference,  he  would  certainly  be 
acquitted  of  the  charge  of  '  making  the  ego  an  illusion '.  But 
what  would  then  become  of  his  realism,  which  seems  to  be 
dearer  to  him  than  his  very  '  self '  ?  He  would  be  accused  of 
making  the  'object'  an  'illusion,'  and  '  subjective  idealism '  is  a 
charge  philosophers  appear  to  dread  as  much  as  politicians  tremble 
at  that  of  anti-democratic  sentiments. 

However  it  is  clear  that  if  the  '  I '  is  allowed  in  this  fashion  to 
absorb  all  '  objects,'  it  must  acquire  in  the  process  all  the  activity 
there  is — which  according  to  Hume  is  not  much.  But  the  difficulty 
will  then  be  how  Dr.  Strong's  egocentric  psychology  is  reconcilable 
with  his  '  realistic '  metaphysic.  I  have  no  doubt  he  has  an  answer, 
but  it  is  not  yet  apparent  to  me. 

On  the  other  hand  I  cannot  admit  that  Dr.  Strong  has  explained 
what  I  call  the  '  personal '  meaning.  He  thinks  he  has,  because  he 
has  considered  a  case  "  in  which  J  mean  an  object "  (p.  70) ;  but 
as  shown  above  it  is  precisely  the  meaning  of  the  '  I '  and  the 
modus  operand*  of  its  meaning  function  that  are  omitted  in  the 
transformation  of  apparent  '  objects '  into  an  '  I '. 

Finally  I  may  remark  that  the  passage  Dr.  Strong  quotes  from 


James  (p.  70),  does  not  seem  to  me  to  be  relevant  to  the  point  at 
issue.  It  illustrates,  not  the  non-existence  of  transitive  and  active 
functions  in  the  psychic  process,  but  the  meaning  of  pragmatic 
verification  by  '  leading  '  or  '  consequences  '.  Unlike  Dr.  Strong, 
James  was  never  oblivious  of  the  empirical  fact  that  experiences 
are  always  owned,  always  '  belong '  to  some  one,  and  did  not  imagine 
that  he  had  '  analysed '  the  '  I '  :  it  is  natural,  however  (though 
mistaken)  for  Dr.  Strong,  who  recognises  no  owner,  to  claim  the 
support  of  the  passages  he  quotes,  precisely  because  he  sees  no 
problem  in  the  '  I  mean  '.  But  James  did,  though  he  did  not  solve 


188       F.  c.  s.  SCHILLEE:  THE  MEANING  OF  'SELF'. 

it.  And  I  incline  to  the  belief  that  no  solution  of  it  is  conceivable 
until  we  abandon  the  coherent  system  of  fictions  which  tries  to 
assimilate  the  method  of  psychology  to  that  of  physics,  and  to 
represent  '  introspection '  as  a  contemplation  of  observable  '  objects,' 
rather  than  as  the  reflective  return  of  an  active  being  on  his  track. 

F.  C.  S.  SCHILLER. 


UNIVERSALS  AND  ORDERS. 

THE  paper  on  '  The  Nature  of  Universals  and  Propositions '  that 
was  read  by  Prof.  Stout  under  the  auspices  of  the  British  Academy 1 
in  December,  1921,  has  opened  up  a  very  important  problem  and 
has  thrown  much  fresh  light  upon  it ;  and,  as  it  seems  to  me  to  be 
closely  connected  with  what  I  have  sought  to  urge  with  regard  to 
the  conception  of  Order,2  I  should  like  to  be  allowed  to  offer  some 
further  observations  on  that  subject. 

Mr.  Stout's  main  contention  is  that  the  qualities  that  belong  to 
an  individual  object  are  themselves  individual  qualities ;  that,  for 
instance,  the  redness  and  roundness  of  a  ball  are  as  definitely  in- 
dividual as  the  ball  itself — as  definitely  distinct,  that  is  to  say,  from 
any  other  redness  and  roundness.  For  this  view  he  makes  out  a 
good  case  up  to  a  certain  point ;  but  what  I  wish  to  indicate  is 
that  his  thesis,  so  far  as  he  succeeds  in  establishing  it,  is  simply  an 
application  of  the  Hegelian  doctrine  of  the  concreteness  of  the 
true  universal  or  notion,  which  is  also  what  I  have  endeavoured  to 
bring  out  by  means  of  the  conception  of  order.  To  Hegel's  own 
statements  on  the  subject  it  is  perhaps  better  not  to  refer  ;  for  the 
technicalities  that  he  uses  are  of  a  kind  that  does  not  readily  com- 
mend itself  to  English  readers.  But  Lotze  set  forth  in  simpler 
language  what  I  take  to  be  the  main  point.  All  that  he  says  in 
Book  I.,  ch.  i.,  of  his  Logic  is  deserving  of  careful  attention ;  but  it 
may  suffice  to  refer  to  two  passages,  in  which  he  distinguishes  be- 
tween the  abstract  universal  and  the  '  true '  universal  which  is 
concrete.  His  statements  do  not  appear  to  have  made  as  much 
impression  as  they  ought  on  English  readers. 

'Abstraction,'  he  says  (§  23),  'is  the  name  given  to  the  method 
by  which  the  universal  is  found,  that  method  being,  we  are  told,  to 
leave  out  what  is  different  in  the  particular  instances  compared 
and  to  add  together  that  which  they  possess  in  common.  If  we 
look  at  the  actual  procedure  of  thought,  we  do  not  find  this  account 
confirmed.  Gold,  silver,  copper,  and  lead  differ  in  colour,  bril- 
liancy, weight  and  density ;  but  their  universal,  which  we  call 
metal,  is  not  found  upon  comparison  by  simply  leaving  out  these 
differences  without  compensation.  Clearly  it  is  no  sufficient  de- 
finition of  metal  to  say  negatively,  it  is  neither  red  nor  yellow  nor 
white  nor  grey;  the  affirmation,  that  it  has  at  any  rate  some 
colour,  is  equally  indispensable;  it  has  not  indeed  this  or  that 

1  Published  by  the  Oxford  University  Press. 

2  MLND,  vol.  xxii.,  N.S.,  No.  86,  and  Elements  of  Constructive  Philosophy, 
Book  I.,  ch.  vii.,  Book  II.,  ch.  v.,  Book  III.,  ch.  iv. 


190  J.  s.  MACKENZIE: 

specific  weight,  this  or  that  degree  of  brilliancy,  but  the  idea  of  it 
would  either  cease  to  have  any  meaning  at  all,  or  would  certainly 
not  be  the  idea  of  metal,  if  it  contained  no  thought  whatever  of 
weight,  brilliancy,  and  hardness.  Assuredly  we  do  not  get  the 
universal  image  of  animal  by  comparison,  if  we  leave  out  of  our 
minds  entirely  the  facts  of  reproduction,  self-movement,  and  res- 
piration, on  the  ground  that  some  animals  produce  their  young 
alive,  others  by  eggs,  others  multiply  by  division,  that  some  again 
breathe  through  lungs,  others  through  gills,  others  through  the 
skin,  and  that  lastly  many  move  on  legs,  others  fly,  while  some 
are  incapable  of  any  locomotion.  On  the  contrary,  the  most 
essential  thing  of  all,  that  which  makes  every  animal  an  animal,  is 
that  it  has  some  mode  or  other  of  reproduction,  of  motion,  and  of 
respiration.  In  all  these  cases,  then,  the  universal  is  produced, 
not  by  simply  leaving  out  the  different  marks  pl  and  p2,  ql  and  g2, 
which  occur  in  the  individuals  compared,  but  by  substituting  for 
those  left  out  the  universal  marks  P  and  Q,  of  which  plp2  and  q:q2 
are  particular  kinds.'  Here  the  objection  to  the  abstract  universal 
is  clearly  brought  out.  But,  in  fact,  it  is  hardly  necessary  to  refer 
to  Lotze  for  this.  Berkeley's  criticism  l  of  Locke's  doctrine  of  the 
formation  of  '  abstract  general  ideas '  might  have  sufficed  for  the 
purpose.  Lotze  proceeds,  however,  a  little  later,  to  give  a  definite 
account  of  the  concrete  universal. 

'  Of  the  true  universal,'  he  says  (§  31),  '  which  contains  the  rule 
for  the  entire  formation  of  its  species,  it  may  rather  be  said  that  its 
content  is  always  precisely  as  rich,  the  sum  of  its  marks  precisely 
as  great,  as  that  of  its  species  themselves ;  only  that  the  universal 
concept,  the  genus,  contains  a  number  of  marks  in  a  merely  indefin- 
ite and  even  universal  form ;  these  are  represented  in  the  species 
by  definite  values  or  particular  characterisations,  and  finally  in  the 
singular  concept  all  indefiniteness  vanishes,  and  each  universal 
mark  of  the  genus  is  replaced  by  one  fully  determined  in  quantity, 
individuality,  and  relation  to  others.' 

Here,  I  think,  we  come  to  the  exact  point  that  Mr.  Stout  was 
insisting  on  in  his  paper.  Let  us  see  how  all  this  can  be  applied 
to  the  particular  instance  of  a  red  ball.  The  ball  has  colour,  shape, 
size,  some  degree  of  hardness,  some  position  in  space-time,  and  no 
doubt  a  number  of  other  characteristics  which  it  is  not  necessary 
to  notice.  We  may  begin  with  colour. 

Colour  is  a  concrete  universal.  It  does  not  mean  something 
that  is  not  red,  blue,  green  or  yellow,  but  rather  something  that 
comprehends  all  these.  When  they  are  placed  in  their  natural 
relations  to  one  another,  as  in  the  spectrum,  they  constitute  what 
I  call  an  order.  In  the  ball  to  which  we  are  referring  one  member 
of  that  order,  red,  has  been  singled  out.  Eed,  however,  is  itself  a 
universal,  and  includes  a  number  of  distinct  shades,  which  also  can 
be  arranged  in  certain  orders,  according  to  degrees  of  intensity, 
saturation,  and  other  characteristics.  In  the  ball,  viewed  at  any 

1  Principles  of  Human  Knowledge,  Introduction,  §§  11  sqq. 


UNIVEESALS  AND  OBDEES.  191 

particular  time,  a  definite  selection  has  been  made  in  all  these 
respects.  It  is  not  merely  red,  but  some  quite  definite  red.  But 
this  is  still  a  universal.  Any  number  of  other  balls  and  of  other 
coloured  objects  might  have  just  that  precise  shade  of  red. 

Similar  remarks  may  be  made  about  the  other  qualities  in  the 
ball.  Its  roundness  is  a  mode  of  shape,  which  could  be  placed 
within  a  definite  order  of  shapes,  ranging  from  the  perfect  globe 
through  a  countless  number  of  deviations  from  that.  The  ball  is 
probably  not  a  quite  perfect  sphere,  but  we  may  suppose  that  it  is 
approximately  perfect.  Even  that  particular  approximation,  how- 
ever, is  still  a  universal.  An  indefinite  number  of  other  bodies 
might  have  just  the  same  approximation.  It  might,  for  instance, 
be  exactly  the  same  approximation  as  that  which  is  found  in  the 
sun  or  in  one  of  the  planets.  And  the  same  is  evidently  true  of  its 
size  and  its  degree  of  hardness.  Its  position  in  space  and  its 
position  in  time,  taken  separately,  may  also  be  shared  by  an  in- 
definite number  of  other  objects,  but  not  its  position  in  space-time. 
Its  position  in  space-time  would  seem  to  be  a  characteristic  that 
belongs  only  to  itself  as  individual.  Hence,  we  might  even  say 
that  space-time  is  pre-eminently  the  individualising  function  in 
existence. 

Looking  at  the  matter  in  this  way,  I  am  led  to  the  conclusion 
that  Mr.  Stout  is  in  error  in  believing,  as  he  says  (p.  3),  that  '  a 
character  characterising  a  concrete  thing  or  individual  is  as  par- 
ticular as  the  thing  or  individual  which  it  characterises  '.  Not 
only  each  particular  quality  of  the  ball,  but  even  the  particular 
combination  of  these  qualities,  might  belong  to  an  indefinite 
number  of  other  balls.  The  only  quality  that  is  its  unique  posses- 
sion is  its  position  in  space-time  and  whatever  follows  from  that  in 
its  relations  to  other  bodies,  in  the  way  of  pressure,  attraction,  and 
the  like.  Now,  if  this  is  the  case,  the  application  that  Mr.  Stout 
makes  of  his  main  contention  would  seem  to  be  only  partly  correct. 
It  will  be  well  to  give  the  application  in  his  own  words. 

'  At  this  point,'  he  says  (p.  10),  '  we  are  confronted  by  the  ulti- 
mate question,  What  is  the  distinction  between  a  substance  on  the 
one  hand,  and  its  qualities  and  relations  on  the  other?  To  me 
only  one  view  appears  tenable.  A  substance  is  a  complex  unity  of 
an  altogether  ultimate  and  peculiar  type,  including  within  it  all 
characters  truly  predicable  of  it.  To  be  truly  predicable  of  it  is  to 
be  contained  within  it.  The  distinctive  unity  of  such  a  complex  is 
concreteness.  Characters  of  concrete  things  are  particular,  but  not 
concrete.  What  is  concrete  is  the  whole  in  which  they  coalesce 
with  each  other.  This  view  of  substance  as  a  complex  unity,  when 
coupled  with  the  doctrine  that  qualities  and  relations  are  universals, 
leads  naturally,  if  not  inevitably,  to  the  denial  of  an  ultimate 
plurality  of  substances.  This  is  the  line  of  thought  which  we  find 
in  Mr.  Bradley  and  Mr.  Bosanquet.  Eeality  must  be  concrete  and 
individual ;  the  individual  cannot  be  constituted  by  any  mere  union 
of  universals.  Yet  if  we  inquire  what  so-called  finite  individuals 


192  j.  s.  MACKENZIE: 

are,  we  find  nothing  but  qualities  and  relations,  which,  as  such, 
are  taken  to  be  universals.  Hence,  the  true  individual  transcends 
the  grasp  of  finite  thought.  There  can  be  only  one  substance,  the 
absolute  and  individual  whole  of  being ;  all  finite  existences  includ- 
ing finite  selves  are  merely  adjectives  of  this.  If  taken  as  ultimate 
they  are  mere  appearances.' 

Now,  I  certainly  think  that  Mr.  Stout  is  right  in  believing  that 
the  view  taken  by  Mr.  Bradley  and  Mr.  Bosanquet  leads  to  pure 
singularism;  and,  it  is  equally  true  that  his  own  view  leads  to 
pure  pluralism.  But  I  see  no  real  ground  for  following  either  line 
of  thought.  Between  singularism  and  pluralism  there  is  what  I 
call  cosmism,  which  follows  from  the  conception  of  concrete  uni- 
versals or  orders  ;  and  the  reading  of  Mr.  Stout's  interesting  paper 
has  only  served  to  confirm  me  in  my  adherence  to  that  third 
alternative.  Indeed,  I  must  confess  that  it  surprises  me  not  a  little 
that  so  many  writers  in  this  country  who  have  been  considerably 
influenced  by  Hegel  seem  to  have  failed  so  completely  to  see  the 
inadequacy  of  the  conception  of  substance.  I  should  have  thought 
that  Hegel's  criticism  of  Spinoza — or  even  Berkeley's  criticism  of 
the  conception  of  material  substance — should  have  sufficed  to  give 
pause  to  the  free  use  of  that  particular  category.  There  seems  to 
be  no  particular  harm  in  calling  a  piece  of  coal  a  substance  and 
inquiring  what  qualities  belong  to  it ;  but  surely  it  would  be  absurd 
to  call  either  Mr.  Bradley  or  Mr.  Bosanquet  or  Mr.  Stout  a  sub- 
stance. I  should  have  supposed  that  they  were  persons ;  and, 
though  it  is  true  that  persons  may  be  said  to  have  certain  qualities, 
such  as  intelligence  (which,  no  doubt,  those  particular  persons  have 
in  a  very  high  degree),  yet,  on  the  whole,  what  have  to  be  ascribed 
to  persons  are  not  qualities,  but  modes  of  action — modes,  in  par- 
ticular, of  thinking,  feeling,  and  willing.  Perhaps  it  is  true  that 
the  qualities  that  are  ascribed  to  a  billiard  ball  or  a  piece  of  coal 
are  also  at  bottom  modes  of  action  ; l  but,  at  any  rate,  the  categories 
of  substance  and  attribute  may  be  used  with  reference  to  such 
bodies  without  doing  them  much  injustice ;  whereas  it  becomes 
ludicrous  to  apply  them  to  persons.  The  absurdity  is  well  brought 
out  in  the  passage  that  Mr.  Stout  quotes  from  Mr.  McTaggart's 
recent  book  (p.  7) — '  A  sneeze  would  not  usually  be  called  a  sub- 
stance, nor  would  a  party  at  whist,  nor  all  red-haired  archdeacons. 
But  each  of  these  complies  with  our  definition,  since  each  of  them 
has  qualities  and  each  is  related  without  being  a  quality  or  relation.' 
It  seems  clear  that  a  definition  that  leads  to  such  a  conclusion 
must  be  a  faulty  one.  A  sneeze  would  seem  to  be  a  complex 
bodily  movement  of  a  living  being ;  a  party  at  whist  is  a  temporary 
mode  of  association  ;  red-haired  archdeacons  are  a  group  based  on 
an  accidental  characteristic.  If  we  have  not  enough  categories  to 
characterise  such  objects,  the  fault  would  appear  to  lie  in  our  list 
of  categories.  To  try  to  bring  everything  under  substance  and  its 
correlatives  is  only  to  create  wholly  unnecessary  absurdities. 

1  Ultimately,  I  suppose,  everything  is  what  it  does. 


UNIVEESALS  AND   OEDEES.  193 

Now,  it  seems  to  me  that  this  has  to  some  extent  been  done,  not 
only  by  Mr.  Bradley  and  Mr.  Bosanquet,  but  also  by  Mr.  Stout 
himself.  Mr.  Stout,  seeking  to  avoid  the  Scylla  of  singularism, 
falls  into  the  Charybdis  of  pluralism.  Cosmism,  as  I  believe, 
enables  us  to  avoid  both  these  errors.  But  I  must  now  try  to 
explain  how  this  is  done. 

The  conception  of  Order,  or  of  the  concrete  universal,  when 
applied  to  the  Universe  as  a  whole,  means  that  it  is  not  to  be 
thought  of  either  as  a  mere  unity  or  as  a  mere  manifold,  but  as  a 
system  containing  a  many  in  one.  Now,  when  a  statement  of  this 
kind  is  made,  it  is  sometimes  said  that  practically  all  philosophers 
are,  in  this  sense,  cosmists ;  but  I  am  afraid  that  that  is  not  the 
case ;  or,  at  least,  most  philosophers  lay  so  much  emphasis  either 
on  the  unity  or  on  the  manifoldness  of  the  world  that  the  other 
aspect  is  almost  completely  ignored.  For  Mr.  Eussell  reality  is  a 
multiverse,  just  as  for  Parmenides  it  was  an  unchangeable  unity. 
Most  others,  no  doubt,  try  to  give  some  degree  of  recognition  to  the 
aspect  that,  on  the  whole,  they  exclude.  Indeed,  even  Parmenides 
and  Mr.  Eussell  may  be  said  to  have  done  this ;  but,  in  so  far  as 
they  do  it,  they  appear  to  be  inconsistent.  No  one  who  attempts 
to  work  out  a  coherent  philosophy  can  altogether  ignore  either  the 
aspect  of  unity  or  that  of  multiplicity,  but  nearly  every  one  tends 
to  stress  one  side  or  the  other  in  such  a  way  as  to  make  the  com- 
plementary side  appear  illusory.  Even  Plato  may  be  held  to  have 
exaggerated  the  aspect  of  unity:  even  Aristotle  may  be  held  to 
have  exaggerated  that  of  multiplicity.  But  Aristotle  at  least  in 
ancient  times  and  Hegel  in  modern  times  may  be  taken  as  among 
the  best  representatives  of  what  I  understand  by  cosmism ;  and, 
lest  it  should  be  supposed  that  I  wish  to  confine  the  term  to 
writers  with  whose  general  views  I  am  in  agreement,  I  may  add 
that  I  should  regard  Mr.  Alexander's  system,  with  which  I  do  not 
agree,  as  being  also  a  good  example  of  what  is  meant.  A  few  re- 
marks about  that  system  may  help  to  make  the  meaning  clear. 

With  the  exception  of  Parmenides  and  of  the  most  exclusively 
monistic  Vedantists,  Spinoza  is,  I  should  suppose,  the  most  perfect 
type  of  a  singularistic  philosopher.  He  is  so,  as  Hegel  noted, 
largely  because  he  took  substance  as  his  fundamental  conception. 
Now,  Mr.  Alexander  reckons  himself  to  be  a  follower  of  Spinoza ; 
and,  in  his  very  interesting  lecture  on  Spinoza  and  Time,  he  has 
explained  how  he  managed  to  escape  from  the  Spinozistic  singular- 
ism.  I  understand  the  explanation  to  be  that  he  made  his  escape 
by  substituting  space-time  for  space  pure  and  simple.  The  Cartesians 
in  general  could  find  no  real  place  for  time.  Descartes  himself 
split  it  up  into  separate  moments,  and  practically  regarded  each 
distinct  moment  of  existence  as  an  independent  universe — the 
only  connexion  between  the  innumerable  universes  lying  in  the 
fact  that  they  are  all  created  by  God.  Spinoza  appears  to  have 
adopted  the  simpler  plan  of  ignoring  time  altogether.  At  any  rate, 
it  does  not  count  for  anything  in  his  system.  Mr.  Alexander,  on 

13 


194  J.    S.   MACKENZIE  :    TJNIVEESALS  AND   OEDEES. 

the  other  hand,  by  recognising  time  as  one  of  the  dimensions  of  the 
universe,  is  able  to  assign  reality  to  the  changing  modes  of 
experience  as  well  as  to  the  formal  unity  within  which  these  modes 
are  comprehended.  He  thus  becomes  in  the  fullest  sense  a  cos- 
mist,  having  both  a  real  unity  and  a  real  multiplicity ;  and  in  this 
way  his  system  must  be  ranked  among  the  most  complete  that  the 
wit  of  man  has  ever  devised.  Its  only  weakness  as  a  system,  so 
far  as  I  can  see,  lies  in  the  fact  that  there  does  not  appear  to  be 
any  real  connexion  between  the  unity  and  the  multiplicity.  Each 
side  has  simply  to  be  assumed.  The  formal  unity  of  space-time 
may,  no  doubt,  be  said  to  demand  the  distinctions  that  are  supplied 
by  the  separate  modes ;  but  there  seems  to  be  nothing  in  the  simple 
nature  of  space-time  as  such  that  could  account  for  the  special 
determinations  that  fall  within  it.  Carlyle  remarked  that  the 
philosophical  problem  of  the  universe  is  like  that  which  was  pro- 
pounded with  reference  to  the  apple-dumpling — how  the  apples 
got  in;  and  this  certainly  seems  to  be  the  chief  problem  that 
remains  in  Mr.  Alexander's  scheme.  If  the  order  of  it  could  be 
reversed — if  it  could  be  seen  that  the  apples  were  essentially  prior 
to  their  covering — the  difficulty  would  perhaps  disappear.  The 
Being  that  comes  in  at  the  end  of  Mr.  Alexander's  scheme  of 
evolution  might  perhaps  serve  to  explain  the  time-process,  if  that 
Being  could  be  regarded  as  its  presupposition  as  well  as  its  goal. 
But  the  system  would  then  bear  more  resemblance  to  that  of  Hegel 
than  to  that  of  Spinoza.  Yet  it  would  not  thereby  lose  any  of  the 
interest  that  lies  in  the  special  details  with  which  Mr.  Alexander 
has  enriched  it.  However,  I  refer  to  this  only  as  an  illustration  of 
what  is  meant  by  cosmism.  What  Plato  called  in  the  Timceus  the 
self-existent  living  being — the  avro  o  IOTI  £<3oi/ — which  does  not 
seem  to  me  to  differ  essentially  from  what  he  called  in  the  Republic 
and  elsewhere  the  Form  of  Good,  may  be  regarded  as  the  great 
concrete  Universal  within  which  all  the  lesser  Orders  find  their 
place ;  and  that  may,  as  it  seems  to  me,  be  regarded  as  the  pre- 
supposition of  all  particular  existences,  as  well  as  the  goal  to  which 
evolution  tends.  Space-time  is  undoubtedly  an  important  Order  : 
it  is  the  Order,  as  I  have  already  indicated,  through  which  finite 
individuality  is  made  possible.  But  it  does  not  by  itself  account 
for  the  qualitative  Orders  of  colour  and  other  sensible  determina- 
tions that  find  their  place  within  the  spatio-temporal  system.  For 
this  we  have  need  of  an  Order  of  a  more  concrete  kind.  Plato,  by 
speaking  of  the  Form  of  Good,  suggests  that  the  Order  of  Value  is 
that  in  which  the  ultimate  explanation  is  to  be  sought ;  and,  by 
speaking  of  the  self-existent  living  being,  he  indicates  the  general 
nature  of  the  reality  that  possesses  supreme  value.  With  both 
these  suggestions  I  should  be  disposed  to  agree ;  and  I  think  their 
significance  can  only  be  properly  appreciated  through  the  full 
recognition  of  the  concreteness  of  the  true  Universal. 

J.  S.  MACKENZIE. 


PLATO  AND  THE  POETS. 

IT  has  often  been  asserted  that  Plato  was  hostile  to  all  poetry,  that 
he  wished  to  banish  poets  and  artists  altogether  from  his  model 
State.  This  view  of  his  doctrine  has  come  down  to  us  from  ancient 
times,  at  least  from  the  fifth  century  of  our  era.  I  find  it  in  Proclus 
and  in  St.  Augustine ;  it  is  assumed  in  the  literary  controversies 
of  the  seventeenth  century,  and  has  been  repeated  again  and  again 
by  representative  scholars  of  our  own  time  down  to  Prof. 
Wilamowitz-Mollendorff's  great  work  upon  Plato  published  two 
years  ago.  Such  a  doctrine  from  a  writer  who  has  been  universally 
acclaimed  as  the  artists'  philosopher  KO.T  e£ox?jv;  who  clinches 
almost  every  argument  with  an  appeal  to  the  Muses  ;  who  has  left 
us  in  the  various  "  myths"  scattered  through  his  dialogues  some  of 
the  most  impressive  prose-poems  that  exist  in  any  language,  would 
seem,  to  say  the  least,  a  little  perplexing.  It  could  only  be  accepted 
as  his  deliberate  teaching  if  it  were  found  definitely  stated  in  ex- 
press terms,  at  different  epochs,  and  especially  if  it  could  be  brought 
into  harmony  with  the  general  trend  of  his  thought  as  exhibited  in 
his  works  taken  as  a  whole. 

I  propose  in  the  following  to  enquire  how  far  the  view  that  poets* 
are  to  be  excluded  from  the  republic  of  Kallipolis  is  justified  by  an 
examination  of  some  of  the  principal  passages  which  refer  to  the 
subject.  They  are  mainly  in  Books  in.  and  X.  of  the  Republic. 

Plato  begins  the  third  book  by  an  enumeration — continued  from 
Book  II. — of  passages  from  Homer,  which  he  says  are  neither 
moral  nor  true  (ovO'  oo-ia  ovr  a\r)0rf),  and  corrupt  those  who  hear 
them.  Such,  Socrates  says,  ought  to  be  excised.  Observe  that 
there  is  not  a  word  about  forbidding  all  poetry,  but  only  of  ex- 
purgating certain  passages  which  tend  to  degrade  the  minds  of  the 
hearers. 

He  now  passes  to  the  form  (Xe'&s,  392  C  sqq.),  and  insists  very 
strongly  on  a  distinction  between  SiTJy^o-is  (narrative)  and  /u/A^o-ts 
(imitation).  The  distinction  seems  to  be  fundamental  in  Plato's 
mind,  but  it  is  not  at  all  clear  what  he  means.1  Sometimes  in  the 
sequel  he  seems  to  imply  that  all  art  is  /xt/x^o-is ;  more  often  he 
draws  a  sharp  distinction  between  imitation  and  other  art.  He 
here  illustrates  it  from  the  opening  episode  of  the  Iliad,  where 
Homer  relates  the  visit  of  Chryses  to  Agamemnon  to  recover  his 
daughter,  continuing  his  speech  in  the  first  person ;  that  is,  he  gives 
the  very  words  of  Chryses,  thus  as  it  were  himself  assuming  the 
character  of  the  person  about  whom  the  story  is  told.  This  Plato 
calls  "  imitation,"  and  as  he  expressly  connects  it  with  tragedy 

1  That  he  does  not  use  the  term  in  the  wider  sense  of  Aristotle's  Poetics 
is  abundantly  clear.  I  shall  return  to  this  point  later  on. 


196  GEO.  AINSLIE   HIGHT  : 

and  comedy  we  may  suppose  that  by  imitation  he  means  dramatic 
poetry;  he  would  like  to  close  the  theatres,  and  so  Adeimantus 
understands  him.  But,  he  says,  there  is  more  than  this.  He 
continues  (394  D)  :— 

What  I  meant  to  say  was  that  we  must  come  to  some  agreement 
as  to  whether  the  poets  should  be  allowed  to  tell  their  story 
by  "  imitation,"  or  whether  only  some  things  should  be 
imitated,  others  not,  and  which  in  each  case ;  or  whether 
they  should  not  imitate  at  all. 

He  does  not  want  to  close  the  theatres,  but  to  regulate  them. 
This  question  he  does  not  deal  with  at  once,  but  passes  on  to  an- 
other, whether  the  Guardians  should  be  imitators,  deciding  it  in  the 
negative,  on  the  rather  curious  ground  that  no  one  can  successfully 
imitate  many  things ;  but  he  again  qualifies  it  (395  C) : — 

But  if  they  do  imitate  let  them  from  childhood  imitate  suitable 
things — the  brave,  the  wise,  the  holy,  the  free,  and  all  such  ; 
what  is  unfree,  or  otherwise  base,  that  they  should  not  do, 
neither  should  they  be  skilled  in  imitating  it,  lest  from  the 
semblance  they  pass  to  the  reality. 

The  difference  is  not  between  imitation  and  narration,  but  as  before, 
between  worthy  and  unworthy  subjects.  Similarly  in  396  B,  C  : — 
There  is  a  certain  kind  of  speech  which  a  fair  and  good  man  will 
naturally  choose  for  his  narrative  when  he  has  anything  to 
say,  and  another  sort,  quite  unlike  it,  which  a  man  of  an 
opposite  nature  and  education  will  affect.  ...  It  seems  to 
me  that  a  decent  person,  when  he  comes  to  tell  about  the 
deeds  or  sayings  of  a  good  man,  will  wish  to  put  himself  in 
his  place.  The  imitation  of  a  good  man,  acting  with  firm- 
ness and  wisdom,  is  not  a  thing  to  be  ashamed  of  ... 
only  when  he  comes  upon  anything  unworthy  of  himself  he 
will  not  care  seriously  to  adopt  the  role  of  one  who  is  his 
inferior,  except  just  as  a  passing  incident. 

Here  the  distinction  at  first  drawn  between  Sujyv/cris  and  /u/Mpo-ts  is 
dropped  altogether ;  what  he  wishes  to  exclude  is  a  debased  sort  of 
art.  Then  follows  the  famous  passage,  398  A  : — 

Should  a  man  so  clever  that  he  can  personate  and  imitate  every- 
thing present  himself  in  our  state  and  wish  to  exhibit  his 
accomplishments,  we  should  make  obeisance  to  him  as  a 
holy  and  wonderful  and  pleasant  individual,  but  should  in- 
form him  that  there  is  no  such  person  in  our  state,  nor 
were  it  right  that  there  should  be.  We  will  anoint  his 
head  with  perfume,  crown  him  with  wool,  and  send  him 
off  to  some  other  city.  For  ourselves,  for  our  own  use,  we 
will  engage  a  more  austere  and  less  pleasing  poet  and  story- 
teller ;  one  who  shall  imitate  the  style  of  things  fitting  and 
proper,  and  shall  deliver  his  message  after  the  fashion  which 
we  approved  in  the  beginning,  when  we  were  endeavouring 
to  train  the  military  officers. 

The  person  expelled  is  not  any  poet,  not  even  the  "imitator"  as 
such,   but   one  pf  those  mountebank   artists  who  pander  to  the 


! 


PLATO  AND  THE  POETS.  197 


popular  taste  for  low  entertainment,  one  who  can  imitate 
barking  dogs,  crowing  cocks,  and  the  like  (c/.,  397  A).  This  is 
confirmed  a  little  later,  where  Socrates  says  in  the  most  emphatic 
language  that  artists  who  follow  what  is  beautiful  and  becoming 
are  to  be  sought  after  (399  A-C ;  401  C-D). 

It  would  be  tedious  to  multiply  passages ;  there  are  many  more, 
in  the  Laws  and  elsewhere,  of  which  I  will  quote  a  selection  at  the 
end.  I  do  not  wish  to  lay  stress  upon  such  sayings  as  that  in  Lysis, 
214  A,  where  he  calls  the  poets  our  fathers  and  leaders  in  wisdom  ; 
or  in  the  Symposium,  209,  where  he  couples  the  names  of  Homer  and 
Hesiod  with  those  of  Solon  and  Lycurgus  as  begetters  of  <f>p6vrj(n<s 
and  all  other  virtue ;  because  they  may  have  been  written  before 
his  thought  was  fully  matured.  Still  they  are  in  keeping  with 
the  rest,  and  with  the  Laws,  which  represents  his  latest  and  most 
advanced  teaching,  where  he  says  (801  A)  that  the  sort  of  poetry 
which  is  of  good  omen  should  be  found  everywhere,  and  with 
Republic,  401  D,  where  he  declares  that  for  education  the  most 
powerful  nourishment  is  to  be  found  in  occupation  with  the  Muses 
(KvpLOiTarrj  ei/  fj.ovc7LKfj  rpo^).  It  is  impossible  in  the  face  of  such  a 
pronouncement  to  maintain  that  he  wished  to  banish  all  art. 

The  tenth  book  opens  with  a  categorical  rejection  of  all 
imitation : 

To  fJ-T/jSa/jifj  7rapa.8ex€<r@ai  avrrjs  oar]  ^I/XT/TIKT/. 

We  will  accept  none  of  it  that  is  imitative. 

Nothing  could  be  plainer,  and  Socrates  declares  that  it  is  the 
thing  which  pleases  him  best  of  all  the  institutions  of  Kallipolis. 
A  little  later  he  adds  in  the  same  vein  (607  B) : 

ciKOTw?  apa  Tore  avryv  IK  rfjs  TrdAews  a7re<rTe'AAo/>iej/  TOLavrrjv  ovcrav. 

We  were  justified  in  sending  it  (poetry)  out  of  the  State,  its  nature 
being  of  such  a  kind. 

Isolated  passages  of  this  kind  occur  in  the  dialogues,  and  are 
liable  on  hasty  reading  to  be  misunderstood ;  but  they  will  not  bear 
examination ;  they  are  always  qualified  in  some  way,  in  this  in- 
stance by  the  words  oo-rj  /xi/op-i/o;  in  the  first  quotation,  and  its 
equivalent  roiam^v  ova-av  in  the  second.  It  all  turns  therefore  on 
the  meaning  of  //.i/x^o-is,  of  which  he  now  gives  a  new  explanation, 
in  accordance  with  his  theory  of  Ideas.  There  are,  he  says,  three 
stages :  Idea — particular  object,  or  imitation  of  the  Idea — artistic 
representation  of  the  particular,  an  imitation  of  an  imitation,  so 
that  poets  are  in  the  third  remove  from  the  truth  (597  E).  He 
then  goes  over  much  of  the  old  ground ;  the  rest  of  this  part  of  the 
dialogue  is  entirely  devoted  to  Homer,  to  showing  that  he  ought 
not  to  be  accepted  as  the  educator  of  Hellas  (606  E-607  A). 

Therefore,  I  said,  O  Glaucon,  when  you  hear  people  lauding 
Homer ;  when  he  is  called  the  educator  of  Hellas,  a  guide 
who  may  with  advantage  be  accepted  for  every  department 
of  human  activity,  by  whose  precepts  everyone  should 
regulate  his  life — when  you  hear  them  talk  like  this,  by  all 
means  welcome  them  kindly;  they  are  excellent  people 
from  their  point  of  view,  and  we  will  agree  that  Homer  is 


198  GEO.   AINSLIE   HIGHT  : 

a  most  poetical  person,  the  first  of  tragedians.  But  they 
must  be  told  that  the  only  poems  which  we  can  accept  are 
hymns  to  the  gods  and  praises  of  good  men.  Once  you 
admit  the  voluptuous  Muse,  whether  in  tones  or  in  words, 
your  city  will  be  ruled  by  considerations  of  pleasure  and 
pain,  not  by  the  standards  which  have  always  been  approved 
as  the  best,  those  of  law  and  reason. 

When  we  remember  on  the  one  hand  the  extravagant  claims  that 
were  put  forward  on  behalf  of  Homer,  how  he  was  regarded,  not 
only  as  a  great  religious  teacher,  but  as  an  inspired  source  of  all 
knowledge,  and  on  the  other  the  monstrous  immorality  and 
aesthetic  repulsiveness  of  some  of  the  conduct  which  he  ascribes  to 
the  gods  of  Olympus,  especially  to  the  supreme  deity,  the  father  of 
gods  and  men,  it  might  occur  to  a  modern  reader  that  a  protest  on 
that  score  from  a  leader  of  Athenian  thought  was  not  only  natural 
but  very  necessary.  It  is  not  a  case  of  overstrained  Puritanism. 
Much  of  the  Iliad  must  have  shocked  a  pious  Athenian  very  much 
as  we  should  be  shocked  by  a  poet  who  should  make  comic  songs 
on  our  sacred  Scriptures.  It  is  Homer's  irresponsible  flippancy 
that  has  roused  Plato's  indignation  and  provoked  his  invective. 
The  reservation  which  he  makes  of  hymns  to  the  gods  and  praises 
of  good  men  is  of  course  capable  of  very  wide  interpretation ;  it 
might  be  understood  to  include  almost  anything — even  the  Iliad 
and  the  Odyssey. 

That  Plato  had  a  standing  quarrel  with  the  poets  in  vogue  in  his 
day  I  do  not  of  course  wish  to  deny.  He  displays  considerable 
animus,  and  sometimes  his  language  towards  them  is  very  harsh. 
We  must  distinguish  between  the  Idea  of  poetry  avro  KaO'avro  and 
its  imperfect  representation  in  the  poetry  of  literature.  Plato's 
polemic  is  directed  against  the  poets  as  he  knew  them  in  Athens  in 
the  fourth  century,  not  against  poetry  itself.  It  is  not  the  Muses 
that  he  wishes  to  banish,  but  the  poets  who  insult  them.  His  own 
word  for  a  person  sunk  in  a  state  of  degraded  ignorance  is  a^ovo-os 
— deserted  of  the  Muses. 

I  return  to  the  question  of  /U/X^CT-IS  and  Plato's  assignment  of 
the  artist  to  the  third  remove  from  truth.  Schopenhauer  in  the 
third  book  of  his  Welt  als  Wille  und  Vorstellung  has  shown  that 
what  the  artist  really  imitates  is  directly  the  Idea,  without  the 
intervention  of  the  particular.  The  same  seems  implied  in  Plato's 
Bepublic,  V.,  472  D  :  otet  av  ovv  .  .  .  and  again  in  VI.,  484  C  :  oWe/a 
ypa</>ets  €ts  TO  aX-rjOtararov  a7ro/3A.€7rovT€9.  Perhaps  this  will  throw 
some  light  upon  what  he  means  by  imitation.  He  must  mean 
what  is  called  "  realism "  in  art,  i.e.,  minute,  uncritical,  vulgar 
accuracy  in  depicting  the  obvious  external  features  of  an  object, 
and  thereby  obscuring  its  organic  unity  as  an  Idea.  I  think  this 
distinction  must  have  been  in  Beethoven's  mind  when  he  wrote 
over  the  Pastoral  Symphony  :  "  Mehr  Empfindung  als  Malerei ". 
That  Plato  had  in  view  the  popular  poets,  artists,  actors,  etc.,  of  his 
own  day  seems  indicated  by  Republic,  III.,  395  D-397  B,  where 


PLATO  AND  THE  POETS.  199 

he  describes  very  vividly  some  of  the  tricks  which  were  practised 
on  the  Athenian  stage — imitation  of  scolding  women,  crowing 
cocks,  bleating  sheep,  creaking  wheels,  drunkards  and  the  like. 
In  Laws,  700,  he  contrasts  the  songs  of  his  day  with  the  good  old 
songs  and  dances  of  a  former  age,  and  traces  the  gradual  degrada- 
tion of  public  taste.  Would  it  be  fanciful  to  suppose  that  the 
moral  and  nervous  strain  of  the  great  war  of  ancient  Hellas  was 
followed  by  an  exhaustion  showing  itself  in  the  vulgarisation  of 
artistic  taste  in  public  representations  not  unlike  that  which  we 
see  in  our  own  day  ? 

We  must  not  unduly  press  consistency  upon  Plato.  So  long  as 
we  hang  upon  the  words  it  must  be  admitted  that  his  language  is 
sufficiently  obscure.  Two  things,  however,  stand  out  very  clearly : 
(1)  That  the  only  poetry  to  be  forbidden  is  that  which  has  a  cor- 
rupting tendency  ;  that  poets  are  not  to  be  allowed  to  mix  poison  with 
their  sweets.  On  the  contrary,  all  that  ennobles,  all  that  tends  to 
make  men  dvSpeiovs,  <r<o0poi/as,  OO-LOVS,  eA.ev#e/oovs  should  be  welcomed 
and  encouraged.  (2)  That  Homer  is  not  to  be  accepted  as  an 
infallible  guide  on  every  conceivable  subject. 

Plato's  doctrine  is  that  of  Euskin  and  of  Eichard  Wagner — I 
believe  of  all  who  have  pondered  much  upon  art — that  the  purpose 
of  art  is  didactic ;  that  poetry  is  not  a  light  diversion  for  leisure 
moments,  but  a  means  of  drawing  the  soul  upwards  to  the  realisa- 
tion of  the  avro  ayaOov.  It  is  opposed  to  the  feebler  doctrine  of 
"  art  for  art's  sake  ". 

GEO.    AlNSLIB   HlGHT. 

OXFORD, 
IQth  November,  1921. 

I  conclude  with  an  enumeration  of  some  of  the  more  important 
passages  in  the  dialogues  which  refer  to  our  subject : — 

On  the  general  question  of  poetry  and  art : — 

Republic,  II.,  379  C,  sqq. ;  III.,  386  A-402  A ;  X.,  595  A ;  603  A- 
608  A.  Laws,  II.,  654  C  ;  III.,  682  A ;  700-701 ;  IV.,  719  B,  C  ; 
VII.,  799 ;  801  A-E ;  810  E ;  816  E-817  D ;  XII.,  967  C,  D. 
Apology,  22  A-C ;  41  A.  Lysis,  214  A.  Symposium,  209  A,  D. 
Gorgias,  501  E-502  E.  Theaetetus,  194  E  (6  -n-avra  o-o^o?  TTOI^TIJ*? — 
perhaps  ironical).  Sophist,  266  D;  268  C.  Phadrus,  245  A; 
278  B,  C. 
On  [j,i[j.r)(n<s : — 

t  Republic,  III,  392  D-397  D ;  X.,  595  A-605  C ;  606  E-607  A. 
Sophist,  236  C ;  267  A,  B. 
On  Homer  : — 

Republic,  II.,  379  C,  sqq. ;  III.,  386  A,  sqq. ;  X.,  595  B;  599  C- 
600  E  ;  607  A.     Ion. 
On  the  character  of  popular  entertainment  in  Athens  :  — 

Republic,  III.,  395  D-397  B.  Laws,  III.,  700  A-701A;  VII., 
789  B,  C. 


ON  CERTAIN  METHODOLOGICAL  ASPECTS  OF  THE  THEORY 
OF  RELATIVITY. 

THERE  are  many  aspects  of  the  Theory  of  Relativity  which  involve 
problems  until  lately  the  exclusive  property  of  Philosophy.  Chief 
among  these  is  the  problem  of  Space  and  Time.  In  the  theory  these 
conceptions  are  given  a  definite  status.  There  are  now  various 
different  views  of  the  characteristics  of  Space,  held  by  different 
writers  on  Relativity ;  and  it  is  a  very  satisfactory  sign  of  the  vigour 
of  modern  physics  that  such  different  systems  as  those  of  Einstein, 
Weyl,  and  Eddington  should  be  elaborated.  The  only  way  of  de- 
ciding between  them  will  be  by  means  of  experimental  tests ;  but 
at  present  no  experimental  test  appears  to  be  available  to  test  the 
theory  of  Weyl  though  it  is  not  impossible  that  some  deduction 
might  be  made  as  to  the  shift  of  the  lines  in  the  spectrum  of  the 
sun  or  perhaps  as  to  the  size  of  the  universe.  But  in  spite  of  the 
fact  that  the  views  of  these  writers  differ  and  there  seems  to  be  no 
way  of  deciding  between  them  at  present,  if  we  eliminate  all  the 
parts  of  the  theory  about  which  there  is  not  agreement,  there  is 
still  something  of  fundamental  importance  in  their  treatment  of  the 
notion  of  Space.  In  the  language  of  modern  logic,  they  all  alike 
use  "  Space  "  as  a  description.1  Space  in  the  theory  of  Relativity 
is  a  constructed  entity. 

To  say  that  space  is  a  description  involves  many  consequences. 
No  description  can  ever  be  used  as  a  proper  name.  We  see  two 
particular  spots  of  colour  and  we  say  "  This  is  darker  than  that  ". 
There  is  in  some  sense,  a  direct  relation  between  the  symbol  "  This  " 
and  one  of  the  spots  of  colour.  Whatever  this  characteristic  may 
be  in  virtue  of  which  "This"  is  in  direct  relation  to  the  thing  in 
the  External  World  to  which  it  refers,  it  is  absent  in  the  case  of 
the  symbol  for  space.  There  is  nothing  in  the  External  World  to 
which  we  can  point  as  being  represented  by  the  symbol.  And  this 
property  of  the  concept  which  makes  it  a  description  involves  a 
further  consequence.  Any  proposition  in  which  the  term  occurs  is 
not  in  its  logically  simplest  terms.  It  can  be  analysed  further. 
And  we  may  easily  see  that  the  analysis  of  such  a  proposition  will 
disclose  some  propositional  function. 

We  may  take  a  simple  example  to  make  our  meaning  plain. 
Suppose  we  are  contrasting  the  heights  of  two  buildings.  If  instead 
of  saying  with  a  wave  of  the  hands  "This  is  loftier  than  that "  we 
say  "  The  building  on  my  right  is  loftier  than  that,"  we  are  using  a 
description.  For  there  is  no  direct  relation  between  the  symbol 

1  The  term  "  Description  "  is  used  in  the  sense  explained  by  Whitehead 
and  Russell  in  Principia  Maihematica,  vol.  i. 


DOEOTHY  WKINCH  :   ASPECTS  OF  THEORY  OF  RELATIVITY.     201 

"The  building  on  my  right"  and  anything  in  the  outside  world. 
The  proposition  can  evidently  be  further  analysed.  We  shall  find 
it  necessary  to  make  use  of  the  prepositional  function  which  may 
be  written  indifferently  f(xy)  or  xE>y. 

f(xy)  =  x  is  to  the  right  of  y  =  xEy. 

And  the  form  of  the  proposition  when  it  is  further  analysed  is 
perhaps;  "  There  is  something  which  is  to  the  right  of  myself  and 
it  is  taller  than  that "  ;  or  if  we  write  it  in  the  symbolism  of  modern 
logic 

g;#  .  xE,a  .  x  is  loftier  than  b 
RX  .f(x,  a)  .x  is  loftier  than  b. 

Or  take  the  case  of  the  proposition  ''Equiangular  triangles  are 
equilateral,"  the  proposition  asserts  that  the  two  properties  of  hav- 
ing equal  sides  and  of  having  equal  angles  always  occur  together  so 
that  neither  triangles  with  equal  sides  and  unequal  angles  nor 
triangles  with  equal  angles  and  unequal  sides  can  exist.  And  we 
may  write  this  proposition 

(x)  .f(x)  .  0  .  g(x) 

(in  which/(#)  means ' '  the  triangle  x  has  equal  angles ' '  and  g(x)  means 
"  the  triangle  x  has  equal  sides  "),  which  may  be  read,  "  Whatever 
triangle  x  may  be,  if  it  has  equal  angles  it  has  equal  sides  ".  Now 
the  characteristics  of  the  symbol  "  The  building  on  my  right," 
which  result  from  the  descriptive  nature  of  the  concept  are  exactly 
those  involved  in  the  treatment  of  space  by  the  relativity  writers. 
A  prepositional  function  is  involved  in  the  analysis  of  any  proposi- 
tion in  which  the  term  "space"  occurs.  And  there  is  nothing 
whatever  in  the  real  world  which  we  are  directly  representing  in 
using  the  term.  All  propositions  such  as  "  Space  is  four-dimen- 
sional "  or  "  Space  is  curved  "  when  analysed  disclose  prepositional 
functions,  and  will  always  be  of  the  form,  "  Whatever  xv  x2,  x3, 
.  .  .  may  be  if  /(x^x^  .  .  .)  then  g(xlx2xs  .  .  .)  ".  Now  scientific 
developments  fall  into  two  classes.  There  is  first  the  collecting 
of  simple  facts  which  attribute  a  certain  character  or  combination 
of  characters  to  individuals.  These  collections  of  facts  together 
with  the  apparatus  of  probability  reasoning  allow  inductions  and 
generalisations  to  universal  propositions  which  make  assertions  as 
to  the  co-existence  of  characters.  The  problems  for  logic  in  this 
domain  are  by  no  means  easy,  involving  difficult  questions  of  the 
validity  of  probability  inference  and  the  study  of  the  notion  of 
probability  itself.  But  beyond  the  setting  out  of  postulates  obeyed 
by  the  relation  between  the  propositions  p  and  q  in  the  assertion, 

"p,  given  data  h,  is  more  probable  than  the  proposition  q  given 
data  k," 

the  difficulties  are  for  the  most  part  in  deciding  what  propositions 
about  the  real  world  shall  be  adopted,  and  not  in  the  working 
out  of  the  implications  of  specific  propositions. 

When  we  arrive  at  the  second  stage  in  scientific  development, 
the  position  is  entirely  different  and  the  difficulty  involved  in  dis- 
covering implications  of  various  propositions  is  often  of  a  high 


202  IDOEOTHY  WEINCH: 

order.  The  problem  here  is  indeed  to  discover  the  relations  be- 
tween the  various  concepts  defined  by  prepositional  functions.  And 
it  is  in  this  domain  that  the  wonderful  mathematical  technique  of 
the  relativity  writers  has  had  such  important  results.  The  theory 
involved  in  Eelativity  is  the  relating  of  various  hypotheses  to  one 
another.  The  achievement  consists  in  establishing  relations  be- 
tween various  properties  which  enable  us  to  see  that  certain  hypo- 
theses about  space  entail  certain  facts  in  the  external  world. 

But  the  older  view  of  space  which  is  directly  contradicted  by  the 
theory  of  relativity,  appears  plausible  in  one  respect.  It  might 
perhaps  be  argued  that  we  have  direct  perception  of  space,  that  we 
see  at  once  that  certain  propositions  are  true,  and  that  we  in  fact 
use  diagrams  with  success  in  very  many  subjects,  including,  for 
example,  biology,  chemistry  and  physics.  Now  the  significance  of 
geometrical  representation  as  it  is  made  use  of  in  non-mathematical 
problems  has  seldom  been  discussed  and  the  fact  that  diagrams  are 
in  use  in  almost  all  the  sciences  as  well  as  in  mathematics  appears, 
prima  facie,  to  be  related  to  the  view  that  space  is  an  entity  which 
we  can  directly  perceive.  But  I  think  that  it  is  possible  to  deny 
this  view  of  space  and  yet  give  a  satisfactory  explanation  of  the 
facts  of  geometrical  and  diagrammatical  representation  of  the  ideas 
of  the  various  sciences. 

During  the  last  few  decades  there  has  been  a  complete  revolution 
of  geometrical  ideas.  Without  this  revolution,  there  could  never 
have  been  a  theory  of  relativity  such  as  we  have  to-day.  From  being 
a  collection  of  propositions  about  a  few  particular  properties, 
Geometry  has  now  developed  into  the  science  of  Classification.  As 
Whitehead  has  pointed  out  in  his  valuable  tracts  on  Geometries,1 
the  classification,  by  means  of  species  and  genera,  of  biological 
entities  into  mutually  exclusive  and  exhaustive  classes  is  a  geometry 
equally  with  the  classification  of  a  finite  number  of  balls  into  classes 
in  various  ways  or  the  familiar  Euclidean  geometry  of  our  youth. 

If  we  adopt  the  modern  view  of  geometry  as  the  science  of  classi- 
fication, we  can  yet  allow  that  diagrams  are  of  use  in  science  with- 
out being  involved  in  any  contradiction.  We  may  take  a  simple 
example  to  make  the  matter  clear.  If  we  take  any  geometry,  there 
are  in  general  a  number  of  propositions  which  give  the  relation  be- 
tween properties  which  can  easily  be  represented,  as  for  example  in 
the  proposition,  "  Whatever  a,  ft,  y  may  be  if  a  is  included  in  ft 
and  ft  is  included  in  y  then  a  is  included  in  y  ".  We  can  represent 
this  by  drawing  a  circle  a  inside  another  circle  b,  which  is  itself  in- 
side a  third  circle  c.  The  relation  of  a,  b  and  c  on  the  paper  gives 
a  representation  of  the  relation  between  any  particular  a,  ft  and  y. 
But  the  proposition  about  any  a,  ft,  y  is  not  as  it  stands  a  geometrical 
proposition.  The  complete  statement  of  the  proposition  would 
contain  the  postulates  which  determine  the  "behaviour"  of  the  re- 
lation of  inclusion.  Different  systems  might  very  well  have  different 

1  Cambridge  Tracts  in  Mathematics,  Cambridge  University  Press. 


METHODOLOGICAL  ASPECTS  OF  THEORY  OF  RELATIVITY.    203 

postulates ;  but  the  effective  results  would  uniformly  be,  "  The 
properties  ^  <j>2  <£3  .  .  .  carry  with  them  the  property  i//".  In  our 
telescoped  proposition  above,  "  If  a  is  included  in  /?  and  fi  in  y  then 
a  is  included  in  y  whatever  a,  /?,  y  may  be,"  we  have  a  proposition 
to  the  effect  that  the  properties — say  fa  </>2  .  .  .  (by  means  of 
which  the  relation  of  inclusion  is  denned)  carry  with  them  the 
further  property  \l/  of  being  transitive.1  Now  a  different  geometry 
of  inclusion  might  have  defined  the  notion  by  means  of  a  set  of 
properties  </>x  i//-  .  .  .  and  then  one  proposition  of  the  system  would 
have  been  to  the  effect  that  the  properties  <£x  ^  .  .  .  carry  with 
them  the  further  property  </>2.  Geometry,  indeed,  consists  in  the 
relating  of  properties  inter  se  and  is  far  removed  from  the  fact  that 
a  circle  a  which  is  included  in  another  circle  b  is  also  included  in 
the  circle  c  in  which  b  lies.  It  is  indeed  as  far  removed  from  this 
fact  as  a  biological  fact  that  a  certain  mammal  is  a  vertebrate  is 
from  the  facts — whatever  they  may  be — of  the  complete  evolutionary 
theory  of  the  co-existence  of  characters. 

Now  in  propositions  about  space  we  are  talking  about  sets  of 
properties.  By  the  name  " mammal"  we  mean  one  set  of  pro- 
perties, by  the  name  "  space  "  we  mean  a  certain  other  specific  set. 
And  we  may  find  it  convenient  to  talk  about  the  "  space  properties  " 
of  entities.  The  final  scientific  account  of  space  will  give  proposi- 
tions to  the  effect  that  some  properties  by  means  of  which  we  de- 
fine certain  relations,  necessarily  entail  certain  other  properties. 
When  propositions  of  this  form  are  established,  it  is  generally  con- 
venient to  manufacture  a  name  for  the  properties  in  question  so 
that  propositions  of  this  form  would  perhaps  read,  "  space  is  curved  " 
or  "  isosceles  triangles  have  two  equal  angles  "  or  "  mammals  are 
vertebrates ".  The  technical  development  of  propositions  of  this 
form  has  been  dealt  with  by  Russell  and  Whitehead  in  their 
Principia  Mathematica.  Now  in  considering  the  theory  of  Relativity 
I  am  concerned  only  with  special  sets  of  properties  and  the  names 
for  them.  But  the  way  in  which  "  space  "  is  used  merely  as  a 
name  for  a  bundle  of  properties  is  entirely  parallel  to  the  way  in 
which,  for  example,  ''atoms  "is  merely  a  name  fora  bundle  of 
properties.  The  logical  status  of  these  names  is  the  same  in  all 
domains  of  scientific  thought.  The  elementary  stage  in  science 
comprising  the  collection  of  particular  facts  is  a  necessary  pre- 
lude, but  only  a  prelude  to  the  more  serious  task  of  discovering 
various  properties  and  grouping  together  sets  of  them  under 
various  names.  Only  in  this  stage  are  we  concerned  with  space 
and  the  inter-relations  of  the  various  properties  which  are  involved. 
It  is,  of  course,  of  great  importance  that  as  many  different  forms  of 
the  hypotheses  used  as  possible  should  be  set  out  (and  such  pro- 
positions are,  of  course,  again  of  the  same  form,  and  assert  relations 
between  properties)  for  the  greater  the  number  of  these  forms  the 

1 A  relation  R  is  transitive  when,  if  x  has  the  relation  R  to  y  and  y  has 
the  relation  R  to  2,  it  follows  that  x  has  the  relation  R  to  z.  Familiar 
examples  are  such  relations  as  "is  greater  than,"  "  is  a  descendant  of". 


204     DOEOTHY  WEINCH  :   ASPECTS  OF  THEOEY  OF  EELATIVITY. 

greater  the  probability  that  suitable  results  will  issue  which  can  be 
tested  by  a  direct  appeal  to  applied  science. 

On  this  view  it  is  evident  that  to  ask,  "  What  is  Space  "  is  not 
significant.  We  want  to  investigate  what  consequences  can  be  de- 
duced from  the  "  space  properties  "  of  terms ;  we  want  to  establish 
as  many  propositions  as  possible  about  the  further  properties  which 
necessarily  belong  to  any  term  possessing  this  set  of  properties. 
We  want  to  trace  the  various  alternative  sets  of  space  properties 
which  are  logically  possible  and  to  see  how  far  results  which  are 
verifiable  can  be  obtained.  It  will  be  very  advantageous  if  pro- 
positions are  discovered  which  make  it  possible  to  apply  tests  to 
decide  between  alternative  theories.  It  will  be  of  great  importance, 
for  example,  if  the  further  development  of  Weyl's  theory  yields 
some  deduction  as  to  the  shift  of  the  lines  in  the  spectrum  of  the 
sun  which  would  enable  us  to  make  a  decision  between  it  and  other 
theories  which  yield  other  results  as  to  the  shift  of  the  lines.  But 
whichever  part  of  the  general  investigation  is  being  undertaken, 
not  in  the  case  of  any  one  of  them  is  it  significant  to  ask,  "  What  is 
Space  ".  It  is  the  properties  and  not  the  intrinsic  nature  of  space 
which  is  the  subject  of  investigation. 

DOROTHY  WBINCH. 


EINSTEIN  AND  IDEALISM. 

AT  a  recent  meeting  of  the  Aristotelian  Society,  where  Lord  Hal- 
dane  presided  over  a  discussion  on  the  Idealistic  interpretation  of 
Einstein's  theory,  Prof.  Carr  tried  to  show  how  his  monadistic 
doctrine  is  the  sole  basis  of  the  Theory  of  Eelativity.  Undoubtedly, 
Prof.  Carr  has  opened  a  new  and  suggestive  track  to  metaphysical 
speculation  by  means  of  the  new  physics  ;  and  one  must  admit  that 
both  the  exposition  and  the  defence  of  his  thesis  have  been  to  his 
credit,  although  he  was  accepting  too  easily  realistic  arguments. 

But  I  question  very  much  whether  the  brilliant  foliage  of 
Einstein's  theory  has  not  hidden  its  very  roots  from  the  perspicacious 
eye  of  Prof.  Carr,  who  gives  too  much  weight  to  mere  analogies. 
At  the  International  Congress  of  Philosophy,  held  at  Oxford  in 
September,  1920,  I  maintained,  as  against  the  crude  subjectivism 
of  Prof.  Eddington  and  the  extreme  absolutism  of  Dr.  Boss,  that 
the  Theory  of  Eelativity  cannot  be  taken  as  a  crucial  system  to  de- 
cide between  idealism  and  realism.  This  view  is  generally  shared 
by  scientists,  who  cannot  profess  a  great  sympathy  for  the  doctrines 
of  those  philosophers  who  endeavour  to  drive  science  on  to  a  cer- 
tain ground  which  is  not  its  own.  I  now  go  further,  and  hold  that 
the  Theory  of  Eelativity  is  rather  a  thing  prejudicial  to  idealism, 
at  least  as  Prof.  Carr  proposes  it. 

I  fail  to  see  how  the  essence  of  the  General  Principle  of  Eela- 
tivity is  to  introduce  in  the  realm  of  physics,  the  very  bane  of  the 
physicist,  subjectivism.  Prof.  Carr  thinks  too  much  of  Einstein's 
observers,  when  he  says  that  Eelativity  shows  that  it  is  impossible 
to  abstract  from  the  mind  of  the  observer  and  treat  his  observations 
as  themselves  absolute  and  independent  in  their  objectivity.  When 
Einstein  speaks  of  observers,  he  does  not  mean  at  all  particular 
active  minds,  as  philosophy  studies  them,  but  mere  beings  belong- 
ing to  different  systems  of  reference  moving  relatively  to  one 
another.  In  other  words,  what  makes  the  difference  in  the  space 
and  the  time  of  two  observers  belonging  to  two  different  systems  of 
reference  moving  relatively  to  one  another,  is  not  the  particular 
mind  of  each  observer,  as  Prof.  Carr  seems  to  think,  but  the  very 
motion  of  their  systems  of  reference,  the  mere  fact  that  they  are 
moving  relatively  to  one  another.  I  do  not  see  any  subjectivism 
here  ;  on  the  contrary,  it  is  an  objective  cause,  i.e.  motion,  which 
makes  all  the  difference  in  the  formulation  of  the  observations  of 
the  two  observers.  And  this  is  so  much  true  that,  in  the  limiting 
case  when  the  two  observers  belong  to  the  same  system  of  refer- 
ence, their  expressions  of  the  same  phenomenon,  with  all  the 


206  THOMAS  GBEENWOOD: 

unfathomable  difference  of  their  minds,  are  identical.  For  them,, 
space  and  time  can  be  taken  as  two  absolutes ;  time  flows  evenly 
for  both  of  them ;  coincidence  in  space  and  simultaneity  are  con- 
tinual experiences  for  them  ;  their  world-lines  are  Euclidian.  The 
philosophical  import  of  this  limiting  case  has  been  overlooked,  be- 
cause its  implications  do  not  clash  with  the  old  physics.  But  in 
fact,  it  challenges  idealism  to  explain  how  the  laws  of  nature  can 
be  looked  at  in  the  same  way  by  many  observers  having  each,  of 
course,  his  own  particular  mind,  and  belonging  to  the  same  system 
of  reference. 

It  is  not  true,  then,  to  say  that  the  work  of  physical  science  is  to 
co-ordinate  the  observations  of  observers,  each  of  whom  uses  his 
own  co-ordinates,  and  for  whom  there  is  no  common  measure. 
The  object  of  physics  is  rather  to  present  natural  phenomena  in  such 
a  way  as  to  be  understood  by  every  particular  mind.  When  Prof. 
Carr  says  then  that  there  is  no  universe  common  to  all  observers 
and  private  to  none,  he  seems  to  harbour  at  the  back  of  his  head 
the  old  Newtonian  ideas  of  an  absolute  space  and  an  absolute  time. 
We  have  been  accustomed,  through  heredity,  to  express  our  ideas 
with  reference  to  an  absolute  space  and  an  absolute  time;  and 
it  is  difficult  to  think  with  reference  to  a  spatio-temporal  uni- 
verse, taken  as  an  absolute  whole.  But  that  is  what  Relativity 
asks  us  to  do  when  dealing  with  physical  science.  If  each  system 
of  reference  has  its  own  space  and  its  own  time,  the  space-time 
considered  as  a  whole,  the  absolute  Universe,  is  a  reality  common 
to  all  observers,  whatever  be  the  relative  motion  of  their  system  of 
reference.  The  enunciation  itself  of  Einstein's  General  Principle 
of  Eelativity  reflects  that  absolute  reality,  independent  of  the  mind 
and  even  of  the  motion  of  the  observers,  absolute  in  its  objectivity 
although  relative  in  its  expressions  by  various  observers.  "The 
laws  of  nature,"  says  the  principle,  "  remain  unaltered  whatever  be 
the  motion  of  the  observers."  What  is  the  very  implication  of  this 
principle?  It  means  that  there  is  an  objective  invariant,  the 
reality  of  which  does  not  depend  on  the  mind,  although  its  expres- 
sion is  affected  by  the  motion  of  the  observers,  not  the  subjective 
activity  of  their  minds.  In  fact,  a  natural  phenomenon  can  be  ex- 
pressed by  the  same  mind,  either  according  to  what  Prof.  Carr 
would  call  the  frame  of  reference  of  the  observer  possessing  that 
mind,  or  according  to  an  infinity  of  frames  of  reference  belonging 
to  different  observers.  All  these  expressions,  by  means  of  an  in- 
definite choice  of  systems  of  reference,  of  the  same  phenomenon 
by  the  same  mind,  give  a  strong  support  to  realism  against  a  subjec- 
tive interpretation  of  the  Principle  of  Eelativity. 

As  a  matter  of  fact,  idealistic  philosophy  and  science  follow  two 
ways  diametrically  opposed  to  each  other.  To  illustrate  this  state- 
ment let  us  call  "  sensible  reality  "  the  world  of  our  direct  perception. 
Now,  idealism  sacrifices  the  second  term  to  the  first :  what  was  a 
sensible  reality  still  remains  sensible,  but  it  is  not  any  more  a 
reality,  for  it  cannot  be  detached  from  consciousness.  Idealism 


I 


EINSTEIN  AND  IDEALISM.  207 

insists  then  on  the  dissociation  of  perception  in  favour  of  pure 
sensation ;  and  our  knowledge  is  confined  to  the  immediate  data  of 
consciousness.  On  the  contrary,  science,  in  its  development,  falls 
upon  the  first  term,  and  progressively  its  concepts  digress  more  and 
more  from  sensation,  they  become  less  and  less  sensible,  while 
their  reality  is  reinforced.  Beality  cannot  become  intelligible,  it 
cannot  become  the  object  of  science  unless  it  is  stripped  of  all  its 
sensible  qualities.  To  constitute  itself,  science  has  to  destroy  the 
singular,  which  is  the  only  reality,  and  create  the  universal,  sub- 
stituting thereby  for  sensible  reality  a  world  of  concepts.  This  seems 
to  lead  to  idealism ;  but  we  must  remember  that  if  science  is  an 
interpretation  of  reality,  such  an  interpretation  presupposes  two 
terms :  mind  and  nature,  independent  the  one  of  the  other. 
Now,  if  the  mind  is  annihilated,  science  would  undoubtedly  dis- 
appear ;  but  reality  will  still  be  there,  although  mutilated,  it  will 
still  exist.  Nature  will  continue  its  performance ;  the  spectators 
only  will  be  missing. 

THOMAS  GREENWOOD. 


VI.— NEW  BOOKS. 

A  History  of  English  Philosophy.     By  W.  R.  SOELEY.     Cambridge  Uni- 
versity Press,  1920.     Pp.  xvi,  380. 

Philosophers  have  often  received  rather  ungenerous  treatment  from  the 
professed  historians  of  our  literature.  If  it  is  not  the  case  with  us,  as  it  is 
with  some  peoples,  that  our  philosophers  have  been  the  greatest  masters  of 
prose  style  in  the  language,  as  Plato  was  incomparably  the  greatest  of 
Greek  prose  writers,  Cicero  (when  quantity  as  well  as  quality  is  taken  into 
account)  of  the  Latins,  Descartes,  Pascal,  Malebranche  among  the  greatest 
of  the  French,  it  is,  at  any  rate,  true  that  several  of  our  philosophers, 
Bacon,  Hobbes,  Berkeley,  Hume — to  mention  no  other  names — are  at  least 
among  the  greater  luminaries,  and  that  no  one  who  is  ignorant  of  their 
writings  can  be  said  to  have  a  really  workmanlike  knowledge  of  what  may 
be  done  with  our  language.  Yet  the  professed  historians  of  English 
Prose  too  commonly  pass  over  such  men  and  their  works  as  something 
"  specialist,"  and  send  the  student  for  his  information  to  text-books  written 
in  the  interests  of  a  philosophical  theory,  where  the  philosophers  as  part 
of  the  inheritance  of  a  nation  with  a  great  literature  are  hardly  appraised 
at  their  full  merits.  All  the  more  welcome  is  a  book  like  this  of  Prof. 
Sorley's,  developed  from  chapters  contributed  to  the  Cambridge  History  of 
English  Literature,  in  which  the  philosophers  receive  their  due  share  of 
attention  as  great  writers  and  powerful  influences  on  the  whole  mental  out- 
look of  their  respective  generations,  and  are  not  degraded  to  the  purpose 
of  "pointing  the  moral"  that  one  will  come  to  confusion  if  one  does  not 
accept  a  particular  -ism,  Benthamism,  Comtism,  neo- Kantianism  or  what 
not.  Prof.  Sorley  treats  his  authors  in  the  right  spirit,  allowing  them  to 
tell  their  own  tale  and  develop  their  own  theories,  without  attempting  to 
make  them  say  what  they  ought  to  say  if  the  reader  is  to  be  directed  into 
the  right  u  ism  "  and  warned  off  the  wrong.  He  is  full  to  the  right  degree 
and  no  further  about  the  big  men,  and  not  too  full  about  the  small  ones. 
~&e  writes,,  as  he  always  does,  gracefully  and  limpidly,  and  there  is  probably 
no  other  work  from  which  the  general  student  of  good  intelligence  can 
learn  so  readily  exactly  what  our  philosophers  have  done  to  shape  the 
general  course  of  the  stream  of  "British  thought "  and  to  create  its  vehicle 
of  expression.  As  far  as  I  can  judge,  the  exposition  is  admirably  full ; 
hardly  anyone  within  the  limits  marked  out  by  the  author,  i.e.,  down  to 
the  end  of  Queen  Victoria's  reign,  is  passed  over.  I  have  barely  noticed 
for  myself  that  perhaps  Aldrich  deserves — from  the  long  vogue  of  his  Artis 
Rudimenta  Logicae  at  Oxford, — something  more  than  a  mere  incidental 
reference  as  an  author  re-edited  by  Mansel,  and  that,  in  my  own  judgment, 
three  most  eminent  men  of  the  nineteenth  century,  John  Grote,  Boole  and 
De  Morgan,  are  treated  to  less  than  due  measure  of  appreciation.  John 
Grote,  though  Cambridge  seems  largely  to  have  forgotten  him,  deserves 
remembrance,  to  my  mind,  as  the  most  incisive  critic  of  J.  S.  Mill's  "con- 
verted "  Utilitarianism,  and  not  less  as  perhaps  the  most  searching  of  all  the 


NEW  BOOKS.  209 

critics  of  the  scientific  Positivism  of  the  palmy  days  of  Huxley,  Tyndall 
and  Clifford.  The  enormous  influence  of  both  Boole  and  De  Morgan  on 
modern  logic  and  modern  views  of  the  mathematical  sciences  is  the  more 
patent  the  more  one  tries  to  follow  the  subsequent  developments.  I 
should  have  said  that  both  were  incomparably  greater  figures,  and  De 
Morgan  an  incomparably  racier  writer,  than  that  now  rather  discredited 
colossus,  Sir  William  Hamilton  the  less  (I  am  not  thinking,  of  course, 
of  his  greater  namesake  of  Dublin). 

If  I  may  venture  one  or  two  other  remarks,  I  hope  they  will  not  be 
taken  as  in  any  way  detracting  from  my  appreciation  of  an  admirably 
full,  admirably  balanced  and  admirably  written  book. 

The  opening  chapter,  with  its  brief  condensation  of  the  whole  mediseval 
period  into  a  few  pages,  strikes  me  as  perfunctory  and  possibly  done 
mainly  at  second-hand.  There  would  be  a  great  deal  to  say  for  excluding 
scholastics,  who  did  not  write  in  our  language  at  all,  from  the  story 
altogether,  but,  if  they  are  to  find  a  place  in  it,  I  cannot  think  that  given 
to  Duns  Scotus  or  Ockham  really  adequate  to  their  historical  importance, 
especially  if  it  is  true,  as  is  sometimes  maintained,  that  the  great  revolt  of 
the  theological  reformers  from  the  traditions  of  the  golden  age  of  scho- 
lasticism was  largely  due  to  the  disintegration  of  scholastic  doctrine  pro- 
duced by  the  influence  of  Ockham.  I  note  (see  p.  92)  that  Henry  More's 
argument  which  establishes  the  necessity  of  God's  existence  by  first  prov- 
ing its  possibility  is  described  in  a  way  which  suggests  that  the  writer  did 
not  know  that  it  is  fully  anticipated  in  the  Scriptum  Oxoniense  of  Scotus 
(as  I  should  suppose  More  knew) ;  it  might  have  been  added  that  Leibniz 
also  proposed  to  complete  the  "  ontological "  argument  of  Descartes  on 
the  same  lines.  The  extreme  exaltation  of  Roger  Bacon  at  the  cost  of  his 
century  in  general  also  seems  to  me  to  indicate  some  want  of  first-hand 
acquaintance  with  the  literature.  I  cannot  myself  conceive  a  competent 
judga  with  real  knowledge  of  the  works  of  both  men  seriously  thinking 
Brother  Roger  the  philosophical  equal  of  the  Angelic  Doctor. 

In  the  account  of  the  early  seventeenth  century,  perhaps  something 
might  be  said  more  than  has  been  said  about  the  influence  of  Ramus  on  our 
literature.  It  is  worth  recording,  e.g.,  that  the  ill-fated  James  Sharp,  not, 
of  course,  yet  a  bishop,  was  lecturing  on  the  Dialectic  of  Ramus  at  St. 
Andrews  in  the  years  1641-43.  Perhaps,  in  connexion  with  page  11, 1  might 
suggest  that  Temple,  Ramus's  English  follower,  selected  the  pseudonym 
Mildapettus  as  a  kind  of  anagram  on  Temple.  At  page  18,  I  should  have 
liked  to  see  a  reference  to  De  Morgan's  penetrating  and  forcible  rejoinder 
(in  the  Budget  of  Paradoxes),  to  Macaulay's  vulgar  and  ignorant  glorification 
of  the  "  Baconian  method  ".  I  doubt  if  there  is  a  saner  and  better  expressed 
discussion  of  Bacon's  proposed  method  of  making  discovery  mechanical,  in 
our  own  or  in  any  language.  On  page  56,  in  connexion  with  Hobbes's  feats 
of  circle-squaring  and  cube-duplication,  it  would  have  been  worth  while  to 
study  these  things  in  Hobbes's  own  writings.  The  interesting  point  is 
that  though  Hobbes's  constructions  are  always  fallacious  and  arbitrary,  he 
had  hold  of  a  real  point  in  his  denunciation  of  Wallis's  Arithmetica  In- 
Jinitorum.  The  development  of  the  nascent  Calculus  was  only  possible  by 
sitting  loose  for  a  time  to  logical  exactness,  and  imagining  infinitesimals 
which  are  at  once  nothing  and  something.  Hobbes's  objection  to  the 
infinitesimal  was,  in  fact,  logically  sound  ;  thanks  to  Weierstrass  and  his 
followers,  the  Calculus  can  now  be  taught  without  any  reference  to  this 
stumbling-block.  There  is  so  much  sheer  confusion  and  wrong-headed 
obstinacy^in  Hobbes's  repeated  attempts  to  prove  such  propositions  as 
TT  =  \/10,  that  he  should,  in  justice,  have  the  credit  of  having  hit  one 
real  logical  blot.  With  reference  to  page  90,  it  might  be  remarked  that 

14 


210  NEW  BOOKS. 

Cudworth's  "Moschus  the  Phoenician "  should  be  Mochus ;  it  was 
Posidonius  who  brought  this  imaginary  person  into  the  history  of 
philosophy  ;  the  confusion  with  Moses  seems  to  be  due  to  some  genius  of 
the  early  Italian  Renaissance. 

In  what  is  said  of  later  writers  of  importance  I  have  little  to  comment 
on  but  three  points.  I  think  the  common  complaint  about  Butler  (see  p. 
164)  that  he  has  not  worked  out  a  theory  of  the  relation  of  conscience  to 
reason  and  will  is  a  little  unreasonable.  Butler's  work  was  not  that  of  the 
constructor  of  an  ethical  theory;  he  was  by  profession  a  preacher  of 
righteousness.  His  audience  in  the  Rolls  Chapel  would  not  have  denied 
that  they  had  consciences,  i.e.,  were  aware  of  a  body  of  moral  obligations, 
and  they  would  have  been  in  fair  agreement,  being  educated  Londoners  of 
the  end  of  George  L's  reign,  about  the  details  of  these  obligations.  What 
they  denied  was  that  they  saw  adequate  reason  to  regulate  their  lives  ac- 
cordingly. Hence  Butler  seems  to  have  been  quite  justified  in  concentrating 
attention  on  the  one  issue  which  was  really  important  for  his  purposes,  the 
"  authoritativeness  "  of  conscience,  and  treating  all  more  speculative  pro- 
blems as  irrelevant.  With  regard  to  Hume,  I  feel  even  in  reading  Prof. 
Sorley's  very  balanced  statement  of  his  position  that  I  am  not  sure  that  it 
is  balanced  enough.  Hume's  Treatise,  as  I  read  it,  certainly  never  teaches 
a  sensationalist  theory  of  knowledge,  or  resolves  causality  and  personality 
into  illusions.  As  I  understand  Hume,  he  argues  that  on  the  one  side, 
Cartesianism  is  an  impossible  doctrine,  on  the  other  sensationalism,  seriously 
thought  out,  makes  physical  and  moral  science  impossible  by  the  very  fact 
that  it  has  to  treat  these  notions  as  illusions.  Neither  of  these  ways  in 
philosophy  is  possible,  and  we  know  of  no  third.  Hence  we  are  committed 
to  scepticism  in  the  proper  sense  of  the  word,  eVo;^,  "refusal  to  affirm  " 
either  of  the  only  two  philosophies  with  which  Hume  is  acquainted. 
Hume's  own  literary  vanity  which  led  him  to  republish  "  elegant  extracts  " 
from  the  unappreciated  Treatise  and  to  disown  the  rest  of  it,  is  chiefly 
responsible  for  what  seems  to  me  the  grave  injustice  commonly  done  to 
his  philosophic  penetration,  but  I  cannot  but  feel  that  it  is  an  injustice 
after  all.  And  with  respect  to  the  Dialogues  on  Natural  Religion  I 
should  go  further  than  Prof.  Sorley.  I  think  Hume  openly  and  re- 
peatedly treats  Philo  with  a  dramatic  irony  which  should  prove,  unless 
Hume  was  wholly  ignorant  of  the  principles  of  dialogue-composition,  that 
he,  at  least,  does  not  represent  his  creator's  convictions.  And,  as  we 
know,  Hume  protested  in  his  letters  against  the  supposition  that  Philo 
was  meant  to  convey  his  own  mind.  Finally,  with  reference  to  page  198, 
should  it  not  have  been  noticed  that  Price  does  more  than  dwell  on  the 
same  ideas  as  Cudworth  ?  Whole  paragraphs  of  Price's  Review  might 
fairly  be  said  to  be  Cudworth's  Eternal  and  Immutable  Morality  trans- 
lated from  pedantic  jargon  into  readable  English. 

A.  E.  TAYLOR. 


Education  and  World  Citizenship.  An  Essay  towards  a  Science  of  Educa- 
tion. By  JAMES  C.  MAXWELL  GARNETT.  Cambridge  University 
Press,  1921.  Pp.  x  +  515.  32s.  net. 

This  volume  is  divided  into  three  books,  of  which  the  first  is  brief  and  in- 
troductory. Book  H.  contains  an  attempt  to  state  the  aim  of  education  in 
terms  of  brain  physiology  and  Book  III.  describes  a  suggested  system  of 
education  for  this  country. 


NEW  BOOKS.  211 

In  his  first  chapter  Mr.  Garnett  utters  a  useful  warning  about  the 
danger  of  metaphor  in  discussions  on  education.  As  he  points  out  many 
obscurities  of  thought  (and  he  might  have  added  much  futility  in  practice) 
have  resulted  from  the  vague  use  of  the  "broad  foundations"  metaphor. 
Unhappily  the  metaphor  has  not  even  been  followed  to  its  logical  issue, 
the  "foundations  "  being  so  often  left  without  any  useful  building  erected 
upon  them. 

Mr.  Garnett,  however,  is  not  content  with  the  abolition  of  metaphor. 
"  For  accurate  and  easy  thinking  about  education  it  is  necessary  to  select 
the  facts  about  which  to  think  and,  above  all,  to  choose  facts  which  are 
simple,  even  if  imaginary,  like  the  line  which  represents  the  direction  of  a 
hedge.  Thus,  in  formulating  principles  of  education,  we  shall  for  the 
most  part  focus  our  attention  upon  the  comparatively  simple  material 
aspects  of  the  brain,  rather  than  upon  the  mind  or  soul,  of  the  person 
being  educated.  This  procedure  implies  no  low  material  view  of  education. 
It  does  not  suggest  that  education  is  concerned  with  the  central  nervous 
system  rather  than  with  the  soul,  although  it  recognises  that  the  soul  can 
only  be  reached  by  human  educators  through  the  brain  of  the  pupil.  Nor 
does  it  assume  that  we  know  more  of  the  brain  than  we  do  of  the  soul  : 
the  contrary  is  more  probably  the  case.  But,  as  Huxley  pointed  out, 
'  there  can  be  little  doubt  that  the  further  science  advances,  the  more  ex- 
tensively and  consistently  will  all  the  phenomena  of  Nature  be  represented 
by  materialistic  formulae  and  symbols '.  Bergson  states  the  same  truth 
more  fully.  'The  intellect,'  he  writes,  'is  characterised  by  a  natural 
inability  to  comprehend  life.'  "  Accordingly,  Mr.  Garnett  sets  forth  the 
generally  recognised  facts  as  to  nervous  arcs  and  their  connexions,  makes 
the  assumption  of  psycho-physical  interaction  while  holding  also  that  all 
mental  phenomena  are  accompanied  by  physiological  phenomena,  and 
taking  further  several  hypotheses  of  McDougall  and  Morton  Prince  as  to 
the  interconnexion  and  interaction  of  neurones  and  their  synapses,  and 
as  to  the  drainage  of  nervous  energy,  he  works  these  with  great  ingenuity 
and  patience  into  an  elaborate  system  according  to  which,  he  holds,  there 
take  place  the  physiological  processes  correlated  with  mental  processes. 

It  is  well  to  keep  clearly  in  mind,  however,  what  Mr.  Maxwell  himself 
admits,  that  at  present  we  know  more  of  the  mind  processes  than  of  the 
brain  processes.  Apart  from  certain  well  recognised  features  of  nervous, 
arcs  and  their  functions,  the  physiology  of  the  brain  processes  corresponding 
to  higher  mental  processes,  is  based  largely  upon  hypotheses  framed  in  the 
light  of  known  psychological  facts,  and  is  checked  by  reference  to  them. 
Consequently,  interesting  and  suggestive  to  the  psychologist  as  may  be  the 
working  out  of  hypotheses  as  to  the  working  of  brain  processes,  it  does  not 
seem  to  afford  us  any  surer  basis  for  educational  theory  than  psychology, 
if  this  be  made  as  exact  as  possible.  If  the  intellect  cannot  formulate 
such  because  of  "  its  natural  inability  to  comprehend  life  "  then  it  cannot 
check  the  truth  of  the  physiological  hypotheses  by  their  correspondence 
with  mental  processes,  and  Mr.  Garnett's  method  seems  to  fall  to  the 
ground. 

In  the  course  of  Book  II.  Mr.  Garnett  formulates  five  "  laws  of  thought  ". 
They  are  as  follows  : — 

I.  To  every  psychosis  there  corresponds  a  neurosis. 

II.  The  Law  of  Diffusion  :  excitement  in  any  nervous  arc  tends  to 
spread  to  every  other  arc  that  is  connected  with  the  first,  through  synapses 
the  insulation  of  which  the  excitement  in  question  is  intense  enough  to 
overcome. 

III.  The  Law  of  Inhibition  by  Drainage  :  any  nervous  arc  of  the  higher 
level,  if  intensely  excited  relatively  to  other  higher  level  arcs,  tends  to 
drain  the  impulses  from  those  other  arcs. 


212  NEW   BOOKS. 

IV.  Will,  measured  by  the  general  factor  (g),  can  reinforce  the  excite- 
ment in  any  excited  system  of  higher  level  arcs. 

V.  Action  is  the  normal  end  of  every  train  of  thought. 

Now  even  from  the  point  of  view  of  brain  physiology  there  seem  to  me 
to  be  grave  difficulties  about  some  of  these  laws.  To  Law  I.  Mr.  Garnett 
himself  seems  to  make  the  primary  activity  of  the  will  an  exception.  Laws 
II.  and  III. — diffusion  and  drainage — seem  to  be  inconsistent  with  one 
another  ;  diffusion  away  from  an  excited  system  or  neurograrn  is  just  the 
opposite  to  drainage  towards  that  system.  The  higher  excitement  of  one 
neurogram  draws  excitement  from  others  but  apparently  it  also  spreads 
to  others. 

Following  McDougall  and  Prince  Mr.  Garnett  regards  the  appearance 
of  volition  as  introducing  a  purely  psychic  influence.  It  cannot  initiate 
a  process  but  it  can  "reinforce  excitement".  The  will  is  supposed  to 
select  a  neurogram  and  reinforce  its  excitement,  using  for  the  purpose 
energy  from  (i)  the  physical  accompaniments  of  attention  (e.g.,  eye-move- 
ments, frowning,  etc.) ;  (2)  organic  sensations  resulting  from  the  stimu- 
lation of  adrenal  glands,  and  (3)  associated  interest  systems. 

The  soul  "  only  intervenes  in  this  way  in  the  event  of  conflict  between 
involuntary  processes  ".  This  relative  isolation  of  the  "  will,"  almost  as  if 
it  were  a  function  independent  of  individual  purposes  and  interest,  seems 
to  me  a  weak  point  in  Mr.  Garnett's  system  and  in  his  otherwise  valuable 
discussion  of  general  ability. 

A  man's  character,  says  Mr.  Garnett,  is  determined  by  (i)  his  neuro- 
graphy  (i.e.,  the  structure  and  inter-relations  of  his  neurograms),  and  (2) 
the  strength  of  his  will  (p.  292).  But  why  not  by  the  direction  of  his  will, 
by  the  type  of  activity  which  the  will  chooses  to  excite  further  ?  For  this, 
according  to  Mr.  Garnett's  view,  is  not  determined  by  the  neurography 
itself. 

The  ideal  citizen  possesses  a  '  single  wide  interest '  supported  by  a  strong 
will.  For  the  community  to  be  ideally  harmonious  and  efficient  the  inter- 
ests of  the  various  citizens  must  be  harmonious,  having  their  basis  in  re- 
ligion. "A  neurogram  of  God"  should  constantly  form  the  central 
element  of  the  single  wide  interest  system.  By  extending  this  line  of 
thought  it  is  inferred  that  since  no  society  can  be  as  progressive  as  possible 
if  its  freedom  to  fulfil  its  common  purpose  is  liable  to  interference  from 
rival  societies  outside  it,  a  "  maximally  progressive  society  "  is  one  that 
includes  the  whole  human  race.  Hence  follows  the  necessity  of  making 
the  aim  of  education  preparation  for  World  Citizenship. 

My  general  impression  is  that  this  book  on  physiological  psychology 
leaves  us  with  no  more  certain,  but  rather  a  less  certain,  basis  for  educa- 
tional theory  than  does  a  purely  psychological  basis  (with  of  course  the  ad- 
dition of  ethical  ideals)  ;  that  Mr.  Garnett's  scheme  of  the  interaction  of 
neurograms  is  less  exact  and  more  vulnerable  even  than  a  psychology  that 
still  uses  the  vaguer  terms  of  mental  life,  after  an  attempt  to  define  them 
clearly. 

Mr.  Garnett  indeed  is  constantly  impelled  to  fall  back  on  some  of  these 
terms  himself ,  especially,  for  example,  the  word  "interest"  ;  and  when  he 
comes  to  direct  psychological  discussion  he  is  sometimes  far  from  happy. 
"  No  one,"  he  writes  (p.  63),  "ever  took  an  interest  in  any  object  about 
which  he  had  not  a  goodly  number  of  ideas  " — an  intellectualist  view  of 
interest  which  would  forbid  the  use  of  the  term  in  describing  the  fascinated 
interest  of  an  infant  or  of  a  young  animal  in  a  novel  object.  Again  Mr. 
Garnett  speaks  of  "  the  images  which  go  to  make  up  a  percept,"  and  refers 
to  the  "thought-activity  in  the  focus  "  gaming  its  meaning  from  thought 
activities  on  the  fringe  of  consciousness,  as  though  "meaning"  were  not 
normally  or  at  least  frequently  focal. 


NEW  BOOKS.  213 

The  fact,  however,  that  this  elaborate  physiological  discussion  does  not 
give  us  any  new  psychological  law  does  not  of  course  mean  that  an  attempt 
to  state  the  probable  physiological  correlation  of  mental  processes  is  use- 
less. Far  from  it.  It  may  be  extremely  suggestive,  as  is  Mr.  Garnett's 
statement  in  many  parts.  Further,  the  possible  modus  operandi  of  such 
physiological  correlations  can  sometimes  be  more  readily  understood  by  the 
student  than  that  of  the  mental  processes  concerned,  and  thus  may  be 
helpful  even  when  the  fact  of  the  particular  mental  process  taking  place  is 
beyond  doubt.  The  type  of  discussion  in  Part  II.  of  the  book  seems  to  me, 
however,  to  be  more  suitable  as  a  study  for  the  student  of  psychology  than 
as  an  introduction  to  the  treatment  of  Education  in  Part  III. 

Indeed  the  third  part  of  this  volume,  in  which  Mr.  Garnett  outlines  an 
excellent  scheme  for  a  natural  system  of  education,  can  stand  fairly  well 
apart  from  the  physiological  foundations  in  Patt  II.  The  weak  points 
usually  owe  their  weakness  to  Mr.  Garnett's  faithfulness  to  his  physiologi- 
cal arguments,  instead  of  to  common  sense  or  generally  accepted  psycho- 
logical doctrines,  as  for  example  when,  in  his  advocacy  of  a  single  wide 
interest,  he  is  led  to  assert  that  "  the  value  of  any  given  expenditure  of 
effort,  whether  by  teacher  or  taught  or  by  both,  decreases  rapidly  with 
the  number  of  separate  subjects  upon  which  that  effort  was  expended. 
We  even  proposed  a  formula  for  ideally  simple  cases,  and  said  that,  in 
such  cases,  the  educational  value  of  the  study  of  a  new  department  of 
knowledge  was  proportional  to  the  square  of  the  time  during  which  the 
study  was  continued,  and  inversely  proportional  to  the  number  of  separate 
subjects  into  which  that  branch  of  knowledge  was  sub-divided." 

Though  Mr.  Garnett  seems  to  me  to  under-estimate  the  value  of  inde- 
pendent interests,  his  plea  for  a  greater  unification  of  educational  studies 
is  a  useful  one,  and  equally  welcome  is  his  protest  against  the  absurdity, 
so  patent  in  our  secondary  school  system,  of  giving  boys  who  are  to  leave 
school  at  fifteen  or  sixteen  the  same  courses  even  during  their  last  year  or 
two,  as  those  given  to  boys  who  are  to  remain  till  eighteen  or  even  to  go 
to  a  University  till  twenty-one  or  twenty- two. 

C.  W.  VALENTINE. 


The  Psychology  of  Day-dreams.  By  J.  VARENDONCK,  with  an  Intro- 
duction by  Prof.  S.  FREUD.  London  :  Allen  &  Unwin,  1921.  Pp.  367. 
18s. 

Dreams  have  been  the  subject  of  a  steady  stream  of  publications,  good 
and  bad — there  appear  to  be  few  indifferent  ones — since  Prof.  Freud  offered 
his  Traumdeutung  to  a  world  at  first  indifferent  and  now  perhaps  a  little 
too  exuberant  in  its  efforts  to  atone  for  the  early  lack  of  welcome.  Nearly 
all  these  essays,  following  their  prototype,  treat  of  the  dreams  which  occur 
during  sleep,  though  many  of  their  writers  must  often  have  been  tempted 
to  investigate  the  day-dream.  That  this  latter  may  be  the  product  of 
mechanisms  similar  to  those  which  fashion  the  sleep-dream  is  quite  con- 
ceivable ;  are  not  Christina's  musings  in  The  Way  of  all  Flesh  delightful 
examples  of  more  than  one  of  Freud's  contentions  ?  Freud  himself,  however, 
appears  to  have  done  little  more  than  to  indicate  the  probable  fruitfulness 
of  this  adjacent  field  to  anyone  who  will  take  the  trouble  to  cultivate  it. 

At  last  a  beginning  in  this  direction  has  been  made  ;  ?ome  preliminary 
furrows  have  been  cut  by  Dr.  J.  Varendonck,  formerly  a  lecturer  in  the 
Paedological  Faculty  of  Brussels.  That  he  has  had  an  extensive  preliminary 
acquaintance  with  some  of  the  results  of  day-dreams,  in  a  related  field  of 
psychology,  is  attested  by  the  titles  of  two  of  his  published  books  ;  La 


'214  NEW  BOOKS. 

Psychologic  du  Te'moignage  and  Experimenteele  Bydrage  tot  de  psychologie 
van  het  getuigenis. 

He  gives  a  proof  of  his  versatility  by  writing  the  present  book  in  English. 
In  its  preface,  apologising  for  his  "linguistic  shortcomings,"  he  explains 
that  he  has  chosen  our  language  because  he  wishes  to  reach  English  readers 
directly,  "as  being,  of  all  nations,  those  who  show  the  greatest  interest  in 
psycho-analysis ".      Dr.  Varendonck  therefore   needs  no  assurance  that 
readers  will  not  be  lacking  who,  appreciating  this  tribute,  will  examine  his 
book  with  sympathy.     And  as  by  this  graceful  action  he  has  become  one  of 
ourselves,   he  will  surely  not  misinterpret  the  spirit  in  which,  in  this 
review,  criticism  is  directed  upon  its  immediate  value  to  English  readers. 
Not  a  few  of  these,  with  the  best  will  in  the  world,  and  the  greatest 
reluctance  even  to  glance  towards  the  mouth  of  a  gift-horse,  will  find 
themselves  compelled  to  question  the  wisdom  of  the  author's  choice  of 
language.     For  there  is  no  disguising  the  fact  that  Dr.  Varendonck 's  book 
is  uncommonly  hard  to  read.     By  this  time  one  has  come  to  regard  the 
process  of  reading  almost  any  new  book  on  psychology  as  inseparable  from 
the   learning   of    new   meanings   for   old  words,    but  Dr.    Varendonck's 
terminology  is  at  times  bewildering.     In  the  first  place,  it  is  difficult  to 
discover  the  principle  underlying  his  choice  of  terms.     Occasionally  he 
seems  to  borrow  from  Wundt,  as  on  page  218.     On  the  next  page  appears 
one  of  the  too  rare  attempts  "  to  state  clearly  the  precise  sense  "  in  which 
"the  technical  terms  of  psychology  "  are  used.     Yet  the  first  term  in  the 
list  which  follows  is  sensation,  which  "we  understand  to  be  the  psycho- 
logical phenomenon  (of  an  affective  or  representative  nature)  resulting 
immediately  from  an  impression  made  upon  the  senses".     Not  every 
psychologist  in  this  country  understands  sensation  in  that  way.     Some- 
times Freud's  own  methods  of  expression  are  employed.     Of  this  it  must 
be  said  that  the  reader  who  finds  Freud's  terms  baffling,  even  in  their 
original  German,  will  have  no  easier  time  with  them  when,  travel-worn 
and  a  little  battered  by  their  journey  to  the  English  language  via  America, 
they  eventually  arrive  bearing  the  meaning  with  which  they  have  been 
imbued  by  a  Belgian  writer.     Prof.  Freud's  introduction  to  the  book  may 
be  cited  as  evidence  that  this  criticism  is  not  unfair,  for  in  it  he  describes 
as  "misleading  and  unsatisfactory"  the  author's  use  of  the  designation 
4  fore-conscious  thinking  '.     Not  a  few  times,  however,  as  in  the  faltering 
uses  of  the  terms  hallucination,  hallucinatory,  illusion,  delusion J — terms 
the  significance  of  which  seems  by  now  to  have  become  constant  in  English 
psychology — Dr.  Yarendonck  does  not  appear  to  have  made  up  his  mind 
as  to  which  meaning  he  is  prepared  to  attach  to  the  words  employed  by  him. 
That  these  points  have  been  insisted  upon  at  some  length,  however  un- 
gracious such  an  action  may  seem,  may  perhaps  be  offset  by  the  obvious 
fact  that  so  much  space  would  not  have  been  given  to  them  if  the  book 
had  been  deemed  less  important.     Though  the  fascinating  glimpses  of  a 
new  psychological  landscape  which  it  gives  can  at  present  be  obtained  only 
by  tiptoeing  and  craning  the  neck  to  look  over  the  intervening  palisading 
of  its  language,  the  attempt,  for  the  person  who  already  knows  some  of  the 
literature  of  psycho-analysis,  is  well  worth  making. 

The  chief  matter  of  the  book  is  divided  into  two  parts,  analytical  and 
synthetical.  In  the  first  part  the  author  explains  how  he  hit  upon  a 
possible  explanation  of  the  fact — as  he  puts  it — that  he  "seemed  to  be 
cleverer  in  bed  than  out  of  it";  that  original  ideas  came  to  him  just 
before  sleep.  On  reading  Freud's  comparison  of  the  psychic  apparatus 
with  a  compound  optical  instrument,  the  constituent  parts  of  which 
Freud  calls  'systems,'  Dr.  Varendonck  asked  himself  "Would  not 

1  Cf.  pp.  109,  110,  134,  146,  183. 


I 


NEW  BOOKS.  215 

these  systems  provide  the  explanation  of  the  abundant  fore-conscious 
ideation  in  the  waking  state  "  ? 

As  a  result,  he  developed  a  technique  of  observing,  recording  and 
analysing  these  day-dreams.  He  retraces,  step  by  step,  all  the  ideas 
which  have  succeeded  one  another  in  his  fore-consciousness.  Starting  from 
the  last  link,  which  he  writes  down  at  once,  he  tries  to  recover  the  last 
but  one,  and  so  on,  "with  the  least  possible  attention  and  the  greatest 
possible  abandonment,"  "till  at  a  certain  moment  all  the  previous  links  of 
the  concatenation  come  together  ". 

The  first  part  of  the  book  is  full  of  such  records.  There  is  no  space  in 
this  review  to  discuss  their  technique,  though  much  might  be  written 
upon  this  subject.  One  question  however  which  is  sure  to  be  asked,  does 
not  seem  to  have  been  adequately  answered  in  advance  by  Dr.  Varendonck. 
To  what  extent,  one  may  enquire,  did  his  own  theories  and  his  natural 
predilection  for  them,  affect  not  only  the  manner  but  also  the  matter  of 
his  day-dreams?  Such  a  question  has  been  asked  often  enough  of  the 
recorders  of  sleep-dreams,  and  in  the  reviewer's  opinion  at  least,  has  never 
been  fully  answered.  In  spite  of  this  even  the  most  ardent  theorist 
among  dream-investigators  is  likely  to  reply  that  though  he  undoubtedly 
finds  many  instances  in  which  his  theoretical  interests  form  the  stuff  of 
his  dreams,  he  fiuds  many  more  concerned  with  themes  of  a  less  lofty 
nature.  But,  a  priori,  it  seems  likely  that  traces  of  the  "pale  cast  of 
thought"  will  be  more  evident  in  the  day-dream  than  in  the  sleep-dream. 
The  one  recorded  on  page  115  even  ends  thus  : — 

"  Immediately  I  say  to  myself  :  '  What  a  beautiful  construction.  I  am 
going  to  write  it  down  at  once,  for  it  contains  a  magnificent  illustration  of 
the  successive  risings  to  the  surface  and  the  sinkings  into  the  unconscious. 
It  entirely  corroborates  my  theory  as  I  have  dimly  constructed  it.'  " 

From  these  studies,  the  author  concludes  that  "the  method  of  fore- 
conscious  thinking  "  is  one  of  concatenated  hypotheses  and  refutations,  of 
questions  and  answers,  "which,"  he  observes,  " is  still  the  most  popular 
manner  of  bringing  fresh  knowledge  to  the  simple-minded ".  As  an 
example  of  this  method  he  cites,  among  others,  the  Roman  Catholic 
catechism  :  he  might  suitably  have  mentioned  here  an  existing  catechism 
in  English  which  deals  with  psycho-analysis  itself. 

It  is  important  to  mention  that  Dr.  Varendonck's  own  thinking  takes 
place  chiefly  in  words.  If  he  had  not  told  us  in  several  other  places  that 
he  is  not  a  well-marked  example  of  the  '  visile  '  type,  his  footnote  to  page  90 
would  have  convinced  us  : — 

"I  have  even  noticed  of  late  that  when  I  happen  to  read  poetry  now  I 
am  able  voluntarily  to  transform  the  poet's  words  into  visual  images,  which 
adds  a  hitherto  unknown  charm  to  the  reading." 

He  praise  worthily  sets  an  example  to  some  of  his  contemporaries  by  keep- 
ing in  mind  the  fact  that  his  own  way  of  thinking  may  not  be  that  em- 
ployed by  everyone  else,  though  unfortunately  in  this  book  he  does  not 
carry  very  far  the  comparison  of  his  day-dreams  with  those  of  visualisers. 
There  seems  to  be  no  reason  why  the  '  question  and  answer  method '  should 
not  employ  visual  terms. 

Continuing  his  description  of  the  contents  of  the  chains  of  fore-conscious 
thought  by  an  account  of  the  way  in  which  they  terminate,  he  suggests  that 
"distraction  is  directly  the  opposite  of  inspiration,  for  in  the  latter  opera- 
tion the  streams  of  thought  (conscious  and  fore-conscious)  flow  towards  the 
same  end  while  in  the  former  they  diverge  ".  This  topic  of  inspiration  is 
very  dear  to  him,  for  dotted  here  and  there  throughout  the  book  there  are 
brief,  almost  breathless,  little  first-hand  descriptions  of  this  experience,  and 
speculations  concerning  its  nature.  He  does  not  forget  to  record,  too,  the 
insomnia  which  is  often  part  of  the  price  paid  for  it. 


216  NEW  BOOKS. 

On  page  179  he  summarises  his  view  of  the  day-dream  : — 

"  1.  A  fore-conscious  chain  of  thoughts  is  a  succession  of  hypotheses  and 
rejoinders,  of  questions  and  answers,  occasionally  interrupted  by  memory 
hallucinations. 

"  2.  These  suppositions  and  criticisms  look  like  a  mental  testing  of 
memory  elements  adapted  to  meet  a  future  situation. 

"3.  The  associative  process  is  directed  by  one  or  several  wishes,  and 
is  the  more  unsteady  as  the  directive  wishes  are  weaker. 

"4.  Every  chain  originates  with  a  remembrance  that  is,  as  a  rule, 
emotionally  accentuated  and  which  is  either  brought  forward  on  the 
occasion  of  an  external  stimulus  or  simply  obtrudes  itself  upon  our  fore- 
conscious  attention. 

"  5.  As  the  chains  progress  their  depth  varies  continually  ;  visualisation 
is  predominant  when  they  proceed  closest  to  the  unconscious  level ;  in  tlie 
reverse  case  verbal  thoughts  prevail ;  but  when  the  ideation  proceeds  in 
images,  the  relations  between  the  visual  representations  are  kept  in  mind 
without  being  represented,  and  only  words  can  render  them  adequately 
when  we  decide  to  communicate  these  phantasies,  which  are  not  meant  for 
commun  ication. 

"6.  They  move  only  in  a  forward  direction,  which  renders  the  later 
correction  of  their  constitutive  parts  impossible  except  through  the 
intervention  of  conscious  functions.  Another  cause  of  errors  is  the  mind's 
unlimited  capacity  for  forgetting  as  well  as  for  remembering. 

"  7.  These  streams  of  thought  are  brought  to  an  end  (before  or  after  their 
aim  has  been  reached)  at  a  moment  of  mental  passivity  under  the 
influence  of  some  affect  which  causes  them  to  rise  to  the  surface,  or  because 
memory  is  set  in  action  in  the  service  of  apperception,  following  upon 
external  stimuli. 

"In  both  cases  the  result  is  a  return  to  the  conscious  state." 

The  second  or  synthetical  part  of  the  book  deals  with  more  general  and 
theoretical  matters.  In  it  the  relations  between  the  *  affect'  and  memory, 
apperception  and  ideation  are  discussed  in  detail.  In  the  first  chapter 
several  interesting  features  of  a  writer's  everyday  life  are  examined,  e.g., 
the  necessity  of  working  when  one  is  'in  the  mood'.  In  this  part  of  the 
book  distinctions  are  rapidly  drawn  between  wish  and  will,  intuition  and 
repression,  affective  and  conscious  thinking,  and  some  of  them  seem  to  be 
at  times  more  puzzling  than  helpful.  ' '  The  history  of  mental  evolution 
teaches  us  that  consciousness  is  mainly  the  result  of  the  successive  repression 
of  our  affects  "  is  a  sentence  which,  in  or  out  of  its  context,  still  tantalises 
the  reviewer. 

In  a  psychological  treatment  of  insomnia  Dr.  Varendonck  suggests  the 
possibility  of  five  varieties  of  psychically  determined  sleeplessness,  and, 
maybe,  penetrates  a  little  deeper  into  a  mystery  the  further  investigation 
of  which  should  yield  very  useful  results.  This  vein  into  which  he  mines 
just  a  little  farther  than  his  predecessors  is  one  which  it  is  hoped  he  will 
not  abandon ;  for  not  only  has  the  advancement  of  science  so  far  done 
comparatively  little  to  strengthen  the  doctor's  hands  in  dealing  rationally 
with  insomnia,  but  the  recent  improvements  which  have  come  about  have 
been  almost  entirely  due  to  increased  knowledge  of  psychological  methods 
of  treatment. 

It  is  impossible  to  characterise  this  book  in  a  few  sentences.  A  critical 
attitude  towards  the  works  of  Prof.  Freud  and  Dr.  Jung  would  enhance  its 
value.  The  '  wish  theory '  of  night-dreams  seems  never  to  be  questioned — 
the  countless  terror-dreams  of  the  war  notwithstanding — though  the  book 
is  published  in  1921.  Jung's  views,  as  expressed  in  his  Psychology  of  the 
Unconscious,  are  mentioned  (p.  303)  with  no  hint  that  any  alternative  or 
supplementary  conceptions  have  been  considered.  The  author's  opinion 


NEW  BOOKS.  217 

(p.  26)  that  "in  the  matter  of  research  it  is  best  to  go  one's  own  way"  is 
one  with  which  many  people  sympathise,  yet  the  wisdom  of  extending  this 
doctrine  to  the  process  of  subsequent  publication  is  questionable. 

The  reviewer  hopes  to  see  at  an  early  date,  a  new  edition,  with  many 
alterations.  He  would  like  too,  to  read  an  edition  in  French.  One 
reason  for  this  would  be  the  interest  of  watching  Dr.  Varendonck's  mind 
at  work  with  another,  and  perhaps,  for  him,  a  more  plastic,  medium  of 
expression. 

T.  H.  PEAR. 


Moral  Theory :  An  Introduction  to  Ethics.     By  G.  C.  FIELD.     London : 

Methuen  &  Co.,  1921.     Pp.  x,  214. 

Common-Sense  Ethics.     By  C.  E.  M.  JOAD.     London:  Methuen  &  Co., 
1921.     Pp.  xvi,  207. 

These  two  books,  coming  from  the  same  publishers  at  '  popular  prices  '  and 
almost  at  the  same  hour,  seem  to  invite  comparison  at  least  in  their 
accidents.  They  are  sharply  contrasted,  however,  in  taste,  spirit,  and 
temper.  Mr.  Field,  scholarly  and  patient,  goes  to  the  great  moralists  of 
the  past,  and  tries,  through  them,  to  make  his  readers  ask  and  understand 
what  the  reason  for  being  moral  truly  is.  Mr.  Joad,  pertinaciously  new- 
fangled, relies  upon  what  he  calls  ' verve'.  Nine-tenths,  at  least,  of 
Mr.  Field's  book,  is  a  connected  argument,  unusually  closely  woven. 
Mr.  Joad  prefers  'impressionistic  methods  and  provisional  generalisa- 
tions'. Indeed,  like  the  new  American  novelists,  he  is  often  willing  to 
let  the  titles  of  his  paragraphs,  in  leaded  type,  do  the  work  of  connecting 
his  story.  And  so  of  other  points. 

The  plan  of  Mr.  Field's  book  is  simple  and  effective.  In  the  first  part, 
he  tries  to  show  his  readers  how  Kant  conceived  the  reason  for  well-doing  ; 
in  the  second  he  examines  how  Aristotle  conceived  it ;  and  he  pursues  the 
quest  towards  a  tenable  theory  in  the  third  part.  Mr.  Joad's  plan,  if 
similar  in  a  way,  is  only  superficially  so.  He  begins,  it  is  true,  with  an 
account  of  traditional  theories,  but  this,  he  tells  us,  is  only  a  '  game  '  and 
the  reader  may  skip  it  if  he  wants  to,  since  the  empirical  or  common-sense 
ethics  about  which  Mr.  Joad  is  really  in  earnest  is  essentially  a  revolt 
against  tradition  and  its  fusty  shibboleths.  Indeed  he  believes  that  the 
roots  of  it  are  planted  in  the  irrationality  of  the  universe. 

Mr.  Field  is  not  a  Kantian,  but  his  exposition  of  the  Fundamental 
Principles,  besides  being  lucid,  careful  and  explanatory,  has  the  signal 
merit  of  trying  to  make  the  reader  see  that  Kant  really  was  discussing 
fundamental  points  in  our  conceptions  of  right  and  wrong.  Moreover,  our 
author  indicates  the  respects  in  which  the  stock  objections  to  Kantianism 
are  matters  of  the  letter  rather  than  of  the  spirit.  He  believes,  however, 
that  Kant  and  many  others  based  their  theories  on  a  fundamental  fallacy, 
and  the  unmasking  of^bhis  fallacy,  together  with  the  constructive  cor- 
rection of  it,  is  the  cardinal  contention  of  his  book. 

This  lethal,  devastating  fallacy  is  the  psychological  assumption  that 
reason  can  be  practical,  and  I  must  frankly  confess  that  Mr.  Field  does 
not  convince  me  at  all.  No  doubt  if  reason  is  defined  as  the  discovery  of 
mere  means  and  of  connexions  of  fact,  then  values  and  ends  are  excluded 
from  its  jurisdiction  by  definition,  but  in  that  case  the  definition  seems 
wholly  arbitrary.  Why  should  the  values  of  ends  be  outside  the  province 
of  reason,  and  why  should  knowledge  of  this  kind  be  impotent  ?  In 
effect,  Mr.  Field  relies  on  the  intuition  that  knowledge  cannot  move,  and 
he  is  so  obsessed  by  this  idea  that  he  actually  identifies  a  'motive  to 


•218  NEW  BOOKS. 

action'  and  a  'reason  for  action'  entirely  sans  phrase  (e.g.,  on  p.  56). 
This  seems  to  me  a  glaring  oversight.  I  can  think  of  no  reason  for  action 
except  the  knowledge  of  worth,  but  I  can  think  of  many  motives  to  action 
or  causes  of  it  which  are  not  reasons  at  all.  And  I  cannot  see  why  these 
moral  reasons  should  not  affect  our  actions.  "It  is  not  mere  knowledge 
that  moves  us  to  action  at  all,"  Mr.  Field  tells  us,  "  if  the  criminal  did  not 
mind  being  hanged,  if  I  am  absolutely  indifferent  whether  I  get  well  or 
not,  then  this  knowledge  would  have  no  effect  on  our  action  one  way  or 
another  ".  Soit :  but  if  the  criminal  had  not  the  faintest  idea  whether  any 
of  his  actions  had  the  remotest  connexion  with  his  being  hanged,  his 
feelings  would  have  no  effect  on  his  action  one  way  or  another,  and  if 
knowledge  does  have  an  effect  on  action,  why  should  not  knowledge  of 
worth  have  its  effect  ? 

Mr.  Field  deals  much  more  tenderly  with  Aristotle  than  with  Kant, 
and  this  is  natural  seeing  that  he  believes  that  '  purpose  is  a  far  more 
fruitful  conception  than  obligation '.  But  certainly  he  is  thorough.  He 
who  snorted  like  a  charger  at  the  notion  of  anything  being  good  in  itself 
purrs  like  a  contented  kitten  at  the  notion  of  ends  which  are  sought 
entirely  tor  their  own  sakes.  But  enough  of  that.  Throughout  his  dis- 
cussion Mr.  Field  is  bent  upon  giving  us  a  modified  Aristotelianism,  and 
the  constructive  argumenfrwith  which  he  supplements  his  excellent  and 
.sympathetic  exposition  of  the  Stagirite,  is  interesting  and  often  valuable. 
Perhaps,  even,  he  makes  the  best  of  his  case.  Some  of  his  readers,  I 
venture  to  think,  will  find  it  desperately  hard  to  believe  that  the  only 
reason  for  being  moral,  or  even  decent,  is  the  fact  that  every  human  being, 
whatever  he  may  happen  to  think,  '  really '  desires  the  *  ideal,'  and  some, 
I  fear,  will  forget  this  theoretical  framework  of  heaven  (which  is  not  in 
the  future)  and  remember  only  that  love  and  affection  (if  possible,  mated 
with  understanding)  are  the  best  things  in  life  according  to  our  author. 
I  hope  they  will  not  forget  the  theory  however.  There  is  no  book  on  ethics 
with  which  I  am  acquainted  that  is  more  persuasively  convinced  of  the 
utter  need  for  hard  thinking  in  moral  enquiries.  From  the  outset  the 
author  takes  his  reader  into  his  confidence,  and  invites  him  to  search  for 
a  reasonable  answer  to  one  of  the  most  important  of  all  questions  ;  and  he 
never  loses  his  frankness,  his  sincerity,  or  his  faith. 

As  we  have  seen,  the  spirit  of  Mr.  Joad's  enquiry,  and  its  considerable 
merits,  are  very  different  from  Mr.  Field's.  As  I  understand  him,  Mr. 
Joad  intends  the  first  part  of  his  book  to  be  philosophical,  logically  water- 
tight, and  all  the  rest  of  it,  while  in  the  second  part  he  is  preparad  to 
throw  logic  to  the  winds  (when  it  suits  him)  in  order  to  reach  '  the  prin- 
ciple at  which  we  happen  to  have  arrived '.  In  the  first  part  he  plays  the 
traditional  game  according  to  the  traditional  rules  (even  to  the  extent  of 
playing  at  a  logical  reconciliation  of  opposing  theories).  In  the  second 
part  he  does  something  better,  for  he  deals  with  life  which  is  larger  than 
logic. 

In  so  very  argumentative  an  author,  this  open  scorn  of  logic  when  he 
ceases  to  be  playful,  seems  somewhat  peculiar.  Indeed,  it  occasionally 
soun,ds  like  '  rationalising '  or  inventing  a  virtue  to  mask  a  troublesome 
uneasiness.  This  suggestion,  however,  is  probably  unfair  to  Mr.  Joad. 
He  seems  to  be  desperately  in  earnest  with  his  ir rationalism. 

At  the  same  time,  he  allows  himself  a  great  deal  of  latitude  both  in  point 
of  logic  and  in  point  of  accuracy,  what  time  he  is  playing  the  traditional 
•game.  Thus,  in  the  matter  of  accuracy,  it  is  surely  preposterous  to  regard 
Kant  as  the  chief  protagonist  of  'moral  sense  theories  '.  To  be  sure,  it  is 
not  at  all  clear  from  Mr.  Joad's  statements  that  '  the  German  philosopher 
Kant'  of  whom  he  speaks  is  really  Immanuel  Kant,  Professor  at  Konigs- 
foerg.  Still  Mr.  Joad,  I  think,  means  to  convey  this  impression ;  and,  if 


NEW  BOOKS.  219 

so,  one  may  be  pardoned  for  wondering  why  he  neglected  to  state  that 
Immanuel  Kant  repudiated  the  moral  sense  (calling  it  a  principle  of 
heteronorny),  and  affirmed  most  explicitly  that  we  have  no  special  sense 
for  good  and  evi\(e,g.,  Metaphysical  Elements  of  Ethics,  Preface).  Again, 
in  the  matter  of  logic,  Mr.  Joad  tells  us  that  the  subjectivity  of  feeling 
makes  it  an  untenable  basis  for  ethics.  This  view,  he  says,  '  cuts  at  the 
objective  basis  of  all  morality '  and  '  nullifies  the  teaching  of  history '.  Yet 
he  informs  us  triumphantly,  only  six  pages  later,  that  '  Good  is  the  object 
of  desire  not  of  reason '.  It  would  be  interesting  to  know  why  the 
subjectivity  of  desires  is  not  an  objection,  or  what  the  momentous  difference 
is  between  Jack  Sprat's  liking  for  lean,  and  his  desire  for  it. 

These  examples  are  not  isolated  but  they  are  sufficient  of  themselves,  I 
think,  to  justify  what  I  have  said.  Moreover,  it  is  hard  to  see  how  Mr. 
Joad's  Part  I.  really  proves  that  traditional  ethics  has  very  little  bearing 
on  life.  In  view  of  the  enormous  influence  of  Benthamism  upon  English 
legislation,  for  example,  it  is  surely  necessary  for  Mr.  Joad  to  explain  with 
rather  special  pains  why  utilitarianism  really  had  nothing  to  do  with  life. 
Instead  of  that  he  tells  us,  with  more  violence  than  care,  that  he  hates 
a  priori  reasoning  and  that  Hobbes  and  Hegel  were  miserable  sinners. 
The  '  game, '  like  angling,  calls  for  patience,  does  it  not  ? 

Mr.  Joad's  Part  II.  presumably  should  be  judged  by  other  standards, 
and  I  do  not  know  what  the  proper  standards  are.  On  the  face  of  it, 
however,  despite  its  disclaimers,  it  professes  to  arrive  at  a  truth  by  some 
sort  of  impressionistic  argument.  This  truth  is  that  ethics  '  becomes 
psychology '  being  simply  a  question  of  how  to  satisfy  the  individual ;  and 
the  basis  of  the  truth  lies  in  metaphysics.  In  common  with  all  things,  we 
are  the  creatures  of  the  Life  Force  which  will  not  let  us  go.  Impulse  is 
the  direct  expression  of  the  Life  Force.  Therefore,  the  life  of  impulse  (so 
far  as  we  can  get  it)  is  the  good  life  ! 

Surely  this  is  very  odd.  "  Impulse,"  says  Mr.  Joad,  "is  the  expression 
of  the  principle  of  change,  reason  of  the  principle  of  conservation  ".  Is 
there,  then,  no  principle  of  conservation  in  our  lives  ?  And  if  there  is 
such  a  principle  what,  on  the  theory,  can  its  source  be  except  the  Life 
Force  ?  Is  it  not  life  that  inhibits  ?  And  is  the  impulse  to  restrain,  to 
ineddle,  and  to  blame  (which  Mr.  Joad  abhors  so  fervently)  not  an  im- 
pulse at  all  ?  Mr.  Joad  is  a  topsy-turvy  Manicheean,  loudly  proclaiming 
that  morality  is  the  devil.  But  there  is  no  room  for  any  devil  in  his 
metaphysics. 

I  suppose,  however,  that  these  remarks  are  not  in  the  proper  spirit. 
Certainly,  they  do  not  touch  the  distinctive  merits  of  the  book.  Mr. 
Joad  sets  out  to  be  lively,  readable,  and  provocative.  He  succeeds.  Also 
he  tries  to  break  new  ground.  And  he  succeeds  again. 

The  chapters  entitled  "The  Psychology  of  Impulse"  and  "The  Place 
of  Impulse  in  Politics  and  Society"  are  by  far  the  most  important  in  the 
book.  In  their  general  outline  these  chapters  follow  the  lead  which  Mr. 
Russell  gave  in  his  Principles  of  Social  Reconstruction,  but  there  is 
nothing  servile  in  Mr.  Joad's  cliscipleship.  Mr.  Joad  develops  and  ex- 
pands con  amore,  and  he  writes  with  refreshing  skill  and  with  manifest 
sincerity.  Whatever  may  be  thought  of  the  sufficiency  of  these  theories, 
and  of  the  larger  background  of  the  new  psychology  and  of  the  new 
politics  in  which  they  are  set,  it  is  at  least  certain  that  moralists  of  the 
present  day  cannot  afford  to  ignore  them.  There  is  a  gap  in  moral  theory 
precisely  at  the  point  which  Mr.  Russell  and  Mr.  Joad  select,  and  there- 
fore there  is  something  more  than  literary  freshness  in  this  gallant  foray 
of  Mr.  Joad's. 

JOHN  LAIRD. 


220  NEW   BOOKS. 

AlleRadici  delta  Morale.     By  ETTORE  GALLT.     "Unitas"  Societa  Edit.,. 

Milan,  1919.     Pp.  414.     Lire  15. 
Nel  Dominio  dell'  "Jo".     By  ETTORE  GALLI.     "Unitas,"  Milan,  1919, 

Pp.  202. 
Nel  Mondo  dello  Spirito.     By  ETTORE  GALLI.     "Unitas,"  Milan,  1919. 

Pp.  250. 

These  three  books  consist  of  elaborate  psychological  studies,  aimed  at 
exhibiting  in  detail  the  author's  view  that  psychology  is  the  true  basis  of 
moral  theory,  and  indeed,  it  would  seem,  of  all  philosophy.  I  may  ob- 
observe  at  once  that  his  hostile  attitude  to  any  doctrine  involving  con- 
siderations of  transcendence  almost  produces  (as  in  Croce  and  Gentile,  with 
whom  otherwise  he  has  nothing  in  common)  a  peculiarity  of  style.  "  Esce 
dalla  vita,"  "in  un  altro  mondo,"  udi  la,"  "fuori  delle  sue  leggi"  (of  the 
psiche),  are  expressions  of  a  type  which  he  constantly  employs  to  characterise 
doctrines  which  belong  to  the  metaphysic  of  ethics  in  its  largest  sense.  I 
am  not  saying  that  he  is  wrong  in  applying  such  language,  e.g.,  to  the  com- 
plete machinery  of  Kant's  ethical  system.  Where  I  should  find  a  difficulty 
would  be  rather  in  his  tacit  postulate  that  metaphysic  has  no  meaning 
except  as  such  abstract  ontology. 

Having  made  this  protest,  I  should  add  that  he  seems  to  me  a  sincere 
and  thoughtful  student,  who  interprets  his  psychology  as  largely  as 
possible,  and  ingeniously  finds  room  in  it  for  most  of  what  a  philosopher 
of  another  type  would  want  to  say,  while  returning  to  remind  us  every  now 
and  then  that  if  we  take  it  beyond  the  province  of  psychological  fact  it  all 
becomes  an  illusion.  He  is,  if  I  follow  him  right,  quite  favourably  dis- 
posed to  this  illusion,  which  he  takes  as  in  fact  inevitable  and  at  the  root 
of  life. 

The  roots  of  morality  are  in  "biological  tendency/'  the  tendency  to  the 
"  utile  "  of  the  organism,  which  is  the  inmost  nature  of  human  and  animal 
impulse,  and  is  not  a  reflective  aspiration  after  pleasure  in  the  abstract. 
It  might  be  described,  I  think,  in  Beccaria's  phrase  as  "  that  force  similar 
to  gravity  which  thrusts  us  on  to  our  wellbeing,"  and  there  are  other  points 
in  the  work  (the  account  of  punishment,  and  of  duty  and  justice)  which 
recall  Beccaria.  The  treatise  consists  of  a  detailed  account  of  the 
gradation  of  conceptions  of  wellbeing  through  which  this  impulse  pushes 
us  onward,  giving  organisation  and  doctrinal  form  by  the  way.  Its  link 
with  our  views  of  life  is  through  the  tendencies  described  as  Optimism 
and  Pessimism,  which  depend  on  the  biological  "  potential "  of  the 
organism.  Optimism,  being  the  reflexion  of  the  tendency  to  life,, 
prevails,  and  with  it  the  ideas  which  are  necessary  to  life. 

Duty,  Justice,  and  Values  are  the  results  in  morality  of  the  "ten- 
dency" ;  but  construed  as  Duty  for  its  own  sake,  as  Justice  involving, 
retribution,  and  as  objective  values  apart  from  desire,  are  misinter- 
pretations of  the  biological  facts  from  which  they  spring,  and  which, 
if  sincerely  and  concretely  interpreted  (Duty  and  Justice  are  means  to  the 
end  of  life)  they  represent  with  fulness  and  truth.  But  the  conclusion 
of  the  whole  matter  is  that  ' '  Psychological  forces  are  the  base  and  the 
secret  stimulus  of  morality.  Morality  is  altogether  a  consequence  of  the 
psychical  constitution  of  the  man  who  lives  it  and  the  philosopher  who 
theorises  it.  Its  objects,  its  principles,  hypostasised  and  located  outside 
of  the  world  and  of  man  to  find  their  justification,  are  the  fruit  of  psycho- 
logical illusion,  are  the  revenge  of  psychology  on  those  who  do  not  take 
due  account  of  it."  I  think,  from  his  own  point  of  view,  he  keeps  con- 
sciousness too  separate,  and  does  not  give  it  its  conative  value  ab  initio. 

The  second  work  is  a  very  detailed  exercise  on  the  formation  and 
characterisation  of  the  ego  by  means  of  the  mine.  The  sense  of  the  mine 


NEW  BOOKS.  221 

is  a  special  case  of  internal  sensation ;  not  feeling,  because  not  pleasure- 
pain — it  might  be  called  "senso";  and  it  is  this  quasi-sensation,  here 
analysed  and  illustrated  at  great  length,  first  as  its  cases  affect  the  ego, 
and  then  as  the  ego's  moods  affect  it,  that  is  the  true  non-conceptual  basis 
of  the  ego.  Comparing  it  with  the  kind  of  sensations  to  which  James 
tended  to  reduce  the  self,  it  seems  more  complete  and  more  relevant.  A 
case  which  has  strongly  impressed  the  author  is  the  sense  of  property  in 
the  Italian  peasant  proprietor,  which  apparently  is  highly  aggressive 
towards  an  intruder. 

The  third  book  contains  disconnected  papers ;  on  Introspection  as  a 
method  (the  only  true  method  of  observation  ;  it  includes  all  observation, 
and,  practically,  deals  with  the  past  and  with  images  only)  ;  on  the  jest 
(Scherzo  or  Burla)  which  has  something  in  common  with  Bergon's  Rire  ; 
and  on  what  the  author  calls  Attesa  in  contrast  to  Attenzione.  This 
shows  his  ingenuity  well,  I  think.  Attesa  is  prospective  attention  which 
implies  an  act  to  be  done.  This  attitude  of  the  whole  self,  underneath 
the  perceptual  observation,  he  compares  with  the  experience  of  waking  at 
an  hour  previously  fixed,  and  this  again  he  likens  to  an  imperative  to 
which  the  whole  subconscious  self  is  adjusted,  as  in  the  moral  imperative. 
You  have  in  such  attention  an  observation  and  a  command.  There  is  a 
criticism  of  the  futurists  which  seems  to  me  plausible,  on  page  126.  They 
try  to  assist  the  imagination  by  supplying  visible  notes  of  incompatible 
times,  but  really  interrupt  and  baffle  it,  by  taking  its  work  out  of  its 
hands. 

The  last  paper  treats  of  freedom  of  the  will,  condemning  the  idea  of 
contingent  or  arbitrary  freedom  as  psychologically  negative,  and  con- 
struing positive  freedom  in  terms  of  the  number  of  alternatives  prepared 
by  mental  process  and  open  to  choice.  This  hardly  meets  the  whole 
difficulty,  which  I  suppose  lies  in  the  determinants  of  the  choice.  Of 
course  I  cannot  agree  with  the  author's  philosophy  which  partakes  of  the 
anti- metaphysical  spirit,  prevalent,  I  imagine  for  historical  reasons,  in 
Italy  to-day.  But  I  think  that  what  he  wishes  to  maintain  has  much 
truth  in  it. 

BERNARD  BOSANQUET. 


Spinoza  and  Time.     By  S.  ALEXANDER.     London  :  Allen  &  Unwin,  Ltd., 

1921.     Pp.  80. 

In  this  small  volume  Mr.  Alexander  repays  a  debt  which  he  seemed  to 
have  overlooked  in  his  monumental  Gifford  Lectures ;  though,  in  fact, 
the  magnitude  of  that  debt  appears  much  less  now  that  it  has  been  ex- 
hibited and  discussed,  than  it  seemed  unacknowledged  but  suspected.  It 
is  well  known  that  in  a  certain  austere  yet  complaisant  mental  attitude 
and  atmosphere,  something  of  the  disinterested  spirit  of  Spinoza  rests 
upon  his  compatriot ;  and  when  to  this  is  added  the  insistence  upon  the 
spatio-temporal  ground  of  Reality  in  Mr.  Alexander's  system,  it  is  not  sur- 
prising that  a  larger  debt  was  imagined  than  a  detailed  study  actually 
reveals. 

It  may  seem,  especially  to  those  who  rely  for  their  interpretation  of 
Spinoza  upon  his  commentators  (and  we  cannot  regard  Mr.  Alexander  as 
belonging  to  that  category,  despite  his  too  modest  remarks  on  p.  19),  that 
it  is  unfortunate  to  cite  the  spatio-temporal  ground  of  Reality  as  a  point 
of  agreement  with  Spinoza  ;  yet  it  must  never  be  overlooked  that  for 
Spinoza  Extension  is  eternal,  which,  if  it  means  anything  at  all,  cannot 
mean  timeless,  except  in  the  sense  in  which  Dean  Inge  speaks  of  timeless - 
ness  as  negating  '  not  the  reality  of  the  present,  but  the  unreality  of  the 


222  NEW  BOOKS. 

past  and  future'  (Outspoken  Essays,  p.  275).  For  Spinoza,  Nihil  in 
ideis  positivum  est,  propter  quod  falsae  dicuntur. 

The  line  of  argument  offered  by  Mr.  Alexander  in  the  present  volume 
is  unique  ;  he  proposes  to  himself  the  question :  What  difference  would 
it  make  to  Spinoza's  philosophy  if  we  *  assign  to  Time  a  position  not 
allowed  to  it  by  Spinoza  himself,  but  suggested  by  the  difficulties  and  even 
obscurities  in  which  he  has  left  it '  (p.  20)  ?  In  effect  what  he  wishes  to 
do  is  to  make  Time  an  Attribute  of  Ultimate  Reality,  and  to  degrade 
Thought  to  the  status  of  a  finite  mode. 

Mr.  Alexander  centres  an  important  part  of  his  criticism  of  Spinoza 
about  the  well-known  discussion  between  the  latter  and  Tschirnhausen 
(Ep.  69-72),  as  to  how  the  variety  of  the  universe  can  be  shown  a  priori 
from  the  conception  of  extension  ;  and  he  indicates  his  view  that  the 
solution  of  Spinoza  (viz.,  that  the  variety  cannot  be  deduced  merely  from 
the  conception,  but  only  through  the  eternal  and  infinite  Attribute)  is 
inadequate  because  he  has  omitted  Time.  And  Mr.  Alexander  quotes  (and 
accepts  as  just)  the  suggestion  of  Mr.  Joachim  that  Spinoza  is  asserting 
that  the  Attribute  differs  from  the  conception  because  it  expresses  God's 
omnipotence,  and  because  Substance  is  alive.  But  life  and  omnipotence, 
he  objects,  '  are  undefined  ideas,  transferred  from  our  experience,  to  de- 
scribe metaphorically  the  being  of  God '.  Doubtless  that  is  true,  I  hold 
no  brief  for  Mr.  Joachim,  nor  do  I  wish  to  read  more  into  the  words  of 
Spinoza  than  his  letter  warrants  (De  his  forsan  aliquando,  si  vita  suppetitf 
clarius  tecum  agam.  Nam  hue  usque  nihil  de  his  ordine  disponere  mihi 
licuit),  but  none  familiar  with  the  mind  of  Spinoza  will  believe  for  a 
moment  that  he  is  guilty  either  of  a  verbal  trick,  or  of  the  vague  generality 
suggested  by  Mr.  Joachim.  Of  course,  as  Mr.  Alexander  asserts,  Spinoza 
would  certainly  have  rejected  the  notion  of  Duration  as  an  Attribute,  and 
in  my  view  he  would  have  been  right  to  do  so,  not  merely  because  it 
would  have  meant  remodelling  his  system,  but  because  the  notion  cannot, 
in  the  end,  sustain  itself. 

In  order  to  bring  that  out  let  us  see  very  briefly  some  of  the  results  of 
Mr.  Alexander's  '  impossible  hypothesis '.  First  of  all,  Infinite  Substance 
goes  and  we  are  left  with  'Stuff'  which  is  identified  with  Spinoza's  im- 
mediate mode  of  Motion.  Finite  things  are  not  '  modes  '  of  '  substance ' 
but  'pieces 'of  'Stuff'.  Then,  Mr.  Alexander  tells  us  that  this  Infinite 
Stuff,  although  full  of  Time,  is  itself  timeless,  in  the  sense  that  it  has 
neither  a  momentary  existence  nor  a  single  duration.  It  '  comprehends 
them  all'.  And  the  only  way  in  which  Mr.  Alexander  can  avoid  the 
difficulty  which  Spinoza  met,  and  which  made  him  exclude  Duration  as 
an  Attribute,  is  by  refusing  to  consider  Stuff  *  as  such '.  But  how  can 
Time  be  an  Attribute  of  Ultimate  Reality  if  that  Reality  is  either  not 
conceivable  '  as  such,'  or  else  is  not  temporal  ?  The  question  we  have  to 
press  is  whether  Duration  is  an  attribute  of  Stuff- as-such.  And  we  cannot 
let  Mr.  Alexander  off  with  metaphors  :  '  The  stuff  of  reality  is  not  stag- 
nant, its  soul's  wings  are  never  furled '  is  no  more  satisfactory  than  Mr. 
Joachim's  metaphor.  Nor,  I  think,  can  Mr.  Alexander  really  avoid  our 
question,  for  he  holds  that  the  grades  of  modal  perfection  proceed,  not  in 
logical  order  as  in  Spinoza,  but  in  temporal  order,  and  that  at  least  sug- 
gests that  Stuff  chronologically  precedes  its  qualitied  '  pieces '.  It  seems 
to  me,  therefore,  that  Mr.  Alexander  asks  us  to  cease  our  analysis  just 
where  we  are  most  interested  in  proceeding  ;  and  we  prefer  with  Spinoza 
to  follow  the  argument  to  the  bitter  end. 

I  make  no  further  reference  to  the  degradation  of  the  Attribute 
of  Thought ;  it  is  based  upon  a  familiar  doctrine  of  Mr.  Alexander's 
Gifford  Lectures.  Nor  have  I  space  for  the  very  important  and  in- 
genious piece  of  Spinoza  scholarship  embodied  in  section  6,  viz.,  the 


NEW   BOOKS.  228 

problem  of  the  apparent  lack  of  symmetry  as  between  Thought  and 
the  infinite  other  Attributes  ;  I  believe  that  Mr.  Alexander  is  here 
working  along  fruitful  lines,  though  the  matter  ought  to  be  capable  of 
an  even  simpler  exposition. 

In  passing  to  the  consequences  for  religion  resulting  from  Mr. 
Alexander's  '  gloss,'  one  may  note  that  he  complains  that  Spinoza's 
God  lacks  'the  human  note,'  because  it  contains  humanity  and  all  other 
things  *  indiscriminately '  ;  it  contains  both  good  and  evil,  and  is  not  in 
the  'lineal  succession  of  goodness'.  Yet  Spinoza  clearly  asserts  :  Probi 
inaestimabiliter  plus  perfectionem  quam  improbi  habent. 

Mr.  Alexander's  general  view  of  the  relation  of  deity  to  Space-Time  and 
to  the  other  qualites  is  well  known.  At  each  level  of  existence  the 
individuals  feel  the  '  nisus '  towards  the  next  higher  level.  For  us  as 
minds  the  nisus  towards  the  quality  of  deity  is  religion.  As  the  object 
of  devotion  God  is  the  infinite  whole  with  its  nisus  towards  deity,  but  no 
infinite  being  possesses  the  quality.  Now  for  us  the  question  is  whether 
such  a  God  better  fulfils  Mr.  Alexander's  own  conditions  than  the  God 
of  Spinoza  ?  Is  it  more  suitable  as  an  object  of  devotion  ?  Does  it  possess 
'  the  human  note '  ?  Is  it  in  '  the  lineal  succession  of  goodness '  ?  Mr. 
Alexander  does  not  here  discuss  the  last  of  these  questions  ;  and  however 
one  might  be  prepared  to  agree  that  his  God,  if  believed  in,  would  be  an 
object  of  admiration  or  fear,  yet  I  cannot  conceive  Him  as  the  object  of  de- 
votion. For  He,  too,  is  lacking  in  the  human  note,  and  devotion  implies  and 
includes  love  for  its  object.  Why  should  I  love  infinite  Space-Time  with 
its  nisus  to  deity  ?  If  Spinoza's  God  lacks  anything,  it  is  that  responsive- 
ness to  love  which  we  enjoy  in  our  fellows,  and  which  love,  as  we  know  ity 
seems  always  (pace  Goethe)  to  demand.  But  I  cannot  feel  that  Mr. 
Alexander  offers  us  even  as  much  as  we  have  in  those  great  words  of 
Spinoza  :  Amor  Dei  erga  homines  et  Mentis  erga  Deum  Amor  intellectually 
unum  et  idem. 

H.  F.  HALLETT. 

Proceedings  of  the  Aristotelian  Society.     New  Series.     Vol.  xxi.  :  1920- 
1921.     London:  Williams  &  Norgate,  1921. 

Dean  Inge's  presidential  address  has  for  title  the  question,  '  Is  the  Time 
Series  reversible  ? '  It  discusses  the  distinction  of  past  and  future,  with 
the  implied  starting-point  of  the  present ;  the  distinction  of  earlier  and 
later,  and  the  meaning  of  the  causal  order  ;  and  finally  the  question,  how 
far  the  hypothesis  of  the  illusoriness  of  the  time  succession  conflicts  with 
the  facts  of  life  and  change.  The  address  is  not  a  long  one  and  maintains 
throughout  an  attitude  of  tentative  suggestion.  Dean  Inge  says,  in  fact, 
that  he  has  not  "even  attempted  to  reach  any  conclusions".  The 
following  sentences,  however,  seem  to  represent  his  own  view,  though  it 
is  left  in  rather  vague  outline.  "The  Time-Succession  seems  tnen  to 
belong  to  a  half-real  world,  and  to  share  its  self-contradictions.  We  are 
partly  in  this  half-real  world,  and  partly  out  of  it.  We  are  enough  out 
of  it  to  know  that  we  are  blind  on  one  side,  which  we  should  never  know 
if  Time  were  real,  and  we  inside  it." 

The  Symposium  on  'The  Character  of  Cognitive  Acts'  by  J.  Laird, 
G.  E.  Moore,  C.  D.  Broad,  and  G.  Dawes  Hicks,  is  an  interesting  one  and 
invites  more  comment  than  I  have  space  to  give  it.  As  is  apt  to  be  the 
case,  the  exact  nature  of  the  question  at  issue  is  not  clear  at  the  outset, 
and  the  third  paper,  Prof.  Broad's,  is  the  most  useful  in  clearing  it  up. 
He  analyses  very  carefully  the  meaning  of  the  question  and  the  possible 
answers  that  may  be  given  to  it.  Sometimes,  however,  his  own  assump- 
tions seem  o  need  some  of  that  critical  questioning  which  he  applies  to 


"224  NEW  BOOKS. 

those  of  others.  "  Why  should  not  ,a  complex  as  a  whole,"  he  asks, 
"  have  the  property  of  being  mental  though  it  consists  of  a  set  of  related 
terms  none  of  which  is  mental  ? "  We  are  expected  apparently  to  swallow 
this  paradox  without  difficulty.  The  only  aid  which  Prof.  Broad  offers  is 
the  suggestion,  "just  as  an  army  has  certain  properties  that  belong  to 
none  of  the  soldiers  in  it ".  But  an  army  has  not,  at  any  rate,  the  pro- 
perty of  being  a  human  complex  none  of  whose  constituents  are  human. 
I  think  the  whole  discussion  might  have  gained  by  being  brought  into 
relation  with  a  well-known  and  fully  worked  out  scheme  of  mental 
analysis  like  Ward's — for  the  reasons,  among  others,  that  Prof.  Ward  has 
insisted  so  strongly  on  the  activity  involved  in  presentation,  and  that  he 
is  careful  about  the  precise  and  appropriate  use  of  terms.  The  present 
discussion  abounds  in  phrases  which  seem  unhappy,  to  say  the  least. 
Thus  an  '  act '  may  have  'objects'  as  'constituents,'  an  'act'  has  'con- 
tents,' a  *  cognition '  may  not  be  an  '  act/  an  object  cannot  *  appear  to 
have  a  character'  save  to  a  '  cognitive  act,'  the  something  that  we  call  '  I ' 
may  be  nothing  distinct  from  and  other  than  '  acts  '.  Prof.  Laird  main- 
tains in  a  vaguer  way  than  Ward  that  the  analysis  of  cognition  requires 
us  to  recognise  an  *  act '  as  well  as  an  '  object,'  but,  on  the  other  hand, 
goes  further  in  claiming  a  direct  introspective  acquaintance  with  the 
'  act '.  Dr.  Moore  and  Prof.  Broad  may  be  said  to  agree  in  questioning 
the  existence  of  any  such  distinct  subjective  factor  and  in  turning  their 
attention  to  the  objective  '  constituents  '  of  the  l  cognition,'  i.e.,  objects  and 
relations  between  objects — a  result  which  is  no  doubt  natural  enough  when 
an  '  act '  is  arrested  for  examination.  In  view  of  the  fact  that  his  analysis 
of  cognition  had  been  directly  challenged.  Prof.  Dawes  Hicks  is  obliged  to 
devote  the  first  part  of  his  paper  to  a  brief  explanation  and  defence  of  it. 
I  wish  he  had  had  space  to  develop  this  interesting  explanation  a  little 
further,  for  I  share  Dr.  Moore's  difficulty  about  the  '  content  '  of  the 
cognitive  act  and  am  not  clear  as  to  its  relation  to  the  '  content  appre- 
hended '.  In  the  second  part  of  the  paper  Prof.  Dawes  Hicks  indicates  the 
relation  of  his  own  view  to  those  of  the  previous  writers. 

Three  papers  deal  with  certain  philosophical  aspects  of  science.  Prof. 
W.  P.  Montague's  on  '  Variation,  Heredity  and  Consciousness '  is  an 
attempt  to  show  (1)  how  some  of  the  facts  of  biology  which  seem  least 
capable  of  being  expressed  in  mechanical  terms — facts  of  Variation  and 
Heredity — can  conceivably  be  so  expressed  if  we  suppose  additional  com- 
plications of  'the  mechanical  apparatus,  (2)  how,  on  the  assumption  of 
parallelism,  the  characteristics  of  consciousness  can  be  reconciled  with  a 
mechanical  theory  of  the  bodily  processes.  As  dealing  with  abstract 
possibilities  the  whole  discussion  is  rather  in  the  air,  and  the  last  part  of 
it  in  particular  is  not  easy  to  follow.  Prof.  J.  E.  Boodin's  paper  on 
'  Cosmic  Evolution '  maintains,  in  a  somewhat  diffuse  and  rhetorical 
fashion,  that  there  must  be  "  an  eternal  hierarchy  of  levels  in  the  universe. 
Law  and  order  on  the  lower  levels  are  due  to  an  interpenetration  by  the 
higher  levels.  .  .  .  These  levels  ...  are  not  mere  abstract  forms,  as 
Plato's  Ideas,  but  energy  patterns."  Miss  Dorothy  Wrinch's  paper  on  the 
'  Structure  of  Scientific  Inquiry  '  insists  on  the  importance  of  developing 
the  logical  relations  between  the  lower  and  the  higher  generalisations  of 
science.  These  generalizations  state  the  co-existence  of  sets  of  properties, 
and  the  logical  problem  of  science  in  its  higher  stage  is  "to  relate  our 
generalisations  among  themselves  so  that  they  follow  inevitably  from  the 
smallest  number  of  unexplained  and  unexplainable  primitive  assumptions  ". 
From  identity  of  form  in  the  logical  scheme  of  relationships  we  may  often 
be  able  to  see  how  the  solution  of  problems  in  one  department  of  science 
covers  those  in  another.  With  these  papers  may  be  grouped  Miss  Hilda 
Oakeley's  '  On  Prof.  Driesch's  Attempt  to  combine  a  Philosophy  of  Life 


NEW  BOOKS.  225 

and  a  Philosophy  of  Knowledge  '  in  which  she  seeks  to  show,  that  in  this 
writer's  later  works  the  philosophy  of  knowledge  is  tending  to  gain  a 
questionable  predominance  over  the  philosophy  of  life,  and  to  deprive  life 
and  history  of  their  due  significance  for  the  final  interpretation  of  reality. 
In  a  paper  called  (not  too  appropriately)  '  The  New  Materialism,'  Mr. 
C.  A.  Richardson  uses  some  of  the  familiar  doctrines  of  Prof.  Ward  as  the 
basis  for  a  criticism  of  Neo-realist  views  in  regard  to  sense-data.  Prof. 
Hoernle's  'Plea  for  a  Phenomenology  of  Meaning'  maintains  that  all 
current  theories  of  meaning  are  inadequate,  and  urges  the  need  for 
"the  collection  and  unprejudiced  examination  of  all  types  of  empirical 
situations  in  which  signs  function  ".  Whether  any  valuable  contribution 
to  philosophy  is  likely  to  reward  the  proposed  labours  is  a  point  on 
which  the  reader  may  have  his  doubts.  In  the  last  paper  of  the  volume, 
'On  Arguing  in  a  Circle,' Dr.  Schiller  contends  that  there  is  no  formal 
distinction  between  arguing  in  a  circle  and  what  he  calls  '  arguing  in  a 
system,'  i.e.,  the  logic  of  Absolutism.  The  argument  contains  too  many 
divisions  and  subdivisions  to  be  easily  summarised,  but  the  following 
quotation  may  serve  to  indicate  the  line  taken,  and  to  show  at  the  same 
time  that  Dr.  Schiller  has  not  wholly  succeeded  in  putting  himself  at  his 
opponent's  point  of  view.  "Just  because  proof  is  held  to  depend  on 
systematic  connexion,  the  complete  system  is  not  capable  of  proof.  The 
proof  must  fall  within  it,  and  none  can  apply  to  the  system  itself.  It  is  a 
corollary  from  this  that  a  (partial)  system  can  be  proved  only  from 
without." 

H.  B. 

The  Making  of  Humanity.     By  EGBERT  BRIFFAULT.     London :  George 
Allen  &  Unwin,  1919.     Pp.  371. 

An  apology  is  due  to  Mr.  Brifiault  for  the  late  appearance  of  this  notice 
of  his  Making  of  Humanity,  a  sequel  to  which  has  been  already  reviewed 
in  MIND.  Mr.  Briffault  is  a  provocative,  a  confident,  and  not  always  an 
accurate  writer  ;  but  those  most  likely  to  be  repelled  by  these  character- 
istics are  perhaps  those  most  likely  to  profit  by  careful  consideration  of 
the  case  which  he  here  presents  with  a  somewhat  one-sided  trenchancy. 
Though  he  opens  with  a  Greek  motto,  he  is  perhaps  not  very  familiar 
with  Greek.  When  we  find  him  speaking  of  Porphyry's  Isagogue,  or  of 
the  pseudo-Dyonisius,  we  may  hope  that  the  printer  is  to  blame  ;  but  the 
printer  can  scarcely  be  responsible  for  the  '  clans,  genoi,  phrateries  '  of 
page  121.  Ignorance  of  Greek  is  not  indeed  a  crime,  but  it  suits  ill  with 
the  contemptuous  tone  of  Mr.  Briffault  in  dealing  with  such  mistakes  of 
scholarship  as  he  detects  (for  example  Alcuin's,  in  speaking  of  kneads). 
His  own  learning  is  much  at  fault  when  he  comes  to  the  middle  ages. 
On  page  216  alone  '  one  Brother  Vergil'  ;  '  John  Erigena  who  had 
travelled  in  the  East '  ;  '  The  eucharistic  heresy  was — it  was  hoped — 
adequately  laid  at  rest  by  Archbishop  Anselm  of  Canterbury  '  ;  '  Abelard, 
who  proclaimed  that  reason  was  the  supreme  and  sole  authority  '  are 
sufficient  to  prove  to  those  acquainted  with  the  subject  how  ill  qualified 
he  is  by  knowledge  of  the  history  of  the  period  to  write  with  such  assur- 
ance about  it.  Of  the  knowledge  of  Aristotle  in  the  west  before  the 
twelfth  century  he  shows  himself  equally  incompetent  to  speak  (one 
would  like  him  to  have  pointed  out  the  *  meagre  fragments '  of  that 
philosopher  to  be  found  in  Capella),  and  what  he  says  of  Averroes  suggests 
that  he  does  not  know  the  thesis  of  Kenan's  book  concerning  him.  His 
cocksureness  about  matters  so  difficult  as  the  influence  of  totemism  and 
the  doctrines  of  Mithraism  do  not  inspire  the  cautious  reader  with  con- 
fidence. One  wonders  what  he  knows  of  *  the  solemn  intonation  of  the 

15 


226  NEW  BOOKS. 

Mithraic  clergy  as  they  called  upon  the  ' '  Lamb  of  God  that  taketh  away 
the  sins  of  the  world  "  '.  Who  could  guess  from  this  passage  that  no 
Mithraic  liturgy  has  come  down  to  us,  with  the  very  doubtful  exception 
of  one  document,  printed  as  such  by  a  German  scholar,  which  contains 
nothing  remotely  resembling  such  a  phrase  ;  or  that  the  victim  in  the 
holy  sacrifice  of  Mithraism  was  not  a  lamb  but  a  bull,  and  that  this 
victim  was  not,  as  in  Christianity,  himself  the  priest  ? 

The  thesis  of  Mr.  Briffault's  book  is  that  '  rationality  of  thought '  is 
'  the  means  and  efficient  cause  of  the  evolution  of  the  human  race,'  '  the 
sole  actual  instrument  of  human  progress  '  (p.  51).  The  '  progress  of 
evolution  '  in  general  '  has  not  been  pre-ordained  or  planned,  but  groping 
and  fumbling'  (p.  22);  but  the  development  of  man,  once  'rational 
thought '  has  taken  it  in  hand,  is  subject  to  laws  which  make  '  the  ideal 
of  an  independent  and  segregated  human  group, '  '  of  a  national  civilisa- 
tion, of  an  empire,  of  a  state  '  '  an  unrealisable  impossibility '.  It  must 
thus  lead  eventually,  we  gather,  to  an  organised  humanity,  and  Mr. 
Briffault,  like  many  of  his  contemporaries,  looks  askance  at  all  theories  of 
national  imperialism  as  attempts  to  hinder  the  movement  in  this  direc- 
tion. It  is  not  without  an  eye  to  people  nearer  at  hand  than  the  ancient 
Athenians  of  whom  he  is  immediately  speaking  that  he  remarks  :  '  A 
league  of  Greek  nations,  such  as  the  Cynic  and  Cyrenaic  philosophers 
advocated  was  all  very  well  before  the  instant  menace  of  Persian  aggres- 
sion, but  as  a  permanent  order  it  was  an  unpractical  dream  '.  '  It  would, 
for  one  thing,  mean  the  giving  up  of  the  command  of  the  sea,  and  that,  of 
course,  was  not  even  to  be  thought  of '  (p.  137).  The  great  enemy  of 
'  rational  thought '  is,  for  our  author,  '  power- thought, '  a  '  functional 
disease  '  of  thought,  '  absolutely  inevitable  and  incurable  '  in  '  the  holder 
of  any  form  of  power  '  (p.  81). 

In  these  contentions  there  is  no  doubt  contained  a  good  deal  of  truth, 
but  one  would  like  to  press  Mr.  Briffault  here  and  there  with  questions 
such  as  these.  How  are  we  to  reconcile  the  statement  on  page  49  that 
'  the  brute-man  first  bethought  himself  of  using  his  brain  as  a  handle  to 
his  tools  and  weapons  '  with  that  on  page  47  which  appears  to  identify 
'  thought '  with  the  use  of  the  brain  cells  ?  Did  '  the  brute-man '  know 
that  his  brain  had  anything  to  do  with  it  ?  What  was  the  origin  of  custom 
(p.  74)  ?  Is  any  form  of  civilisation  conceivable  in  which  no  one  will  hold 
power  and  so  inevitably  succumb  to  the  disease  of  power-thought  ? 

Mr.  Briffault's  views  on  ethics  are  also  not  uninstructive,  although 
again  they  leave  one  unsatisfied  in  certain  points.  The  '  moral  law '  is 
but  '  a  man-made  convention,'  yet  '  it  does  correspond  to  a  very  real  and 
supremely  important  fact  in  human  development '  (p.  260),  namely  that 
( the  peculiar  means  and  conditions  of  human  development  necessitate  that 
that  development  shall  take  place  not  by  way  of  individuals,  but  by  way 
of  the  entire  human  race'.  'Ethical  development,  like  every  other 
aspect  of  human  progress,  not  only  goes  hand  in  hand  with  the  growth 
and  diffusion  of  rational  thought,  but  is  the  direct  outcome  of  it '  (p.  267). 
But  it  is  not  with  the  traditional  moral  code  of  Christendom  that  we  have 
to  do.  The  influence  of  religion  on  ethics  is  in  the  main  viewed  by  our 
author  in  the  spirit  of  Lucretius  :  Tantum  relligio  potuit  suadere  malorum. 
'  Justice  is  the  whole  of  morality  '  (p.  296).  He  is  disposed  to  deprecate 
the  high  value  often  set  on  individual  sanctity  even  apart  from  correctness 
of  judgment.  He  pooh-poohs  the  charge  of  *  corruption '  frequently 
brought  by  prophets  and  satirists  against  complex  civilisations.  He  has 
little  respect  for  the  morality  of  good  intentions,  for  the  '  sincere  and 
disinterested  sense  of  duty  towards  mankind '  which  has  actuated  so  many 
persecutors.  He  is  obsessed  by  'the  wickedness  of  the  "good"'  and 
finds  the  unpardonable  sin  in  our  estimate  of  intellectual  error  as  morally 


NEW  BOOKS.  227 

indifferent  when  our  purpose  is  pure.  Democracy,  though  '  the  worst 
form  of  government,'  is  '  the  only  social  order  that  is  admissible,  becau.se 
it  is  the  only  one  consistent  with  justice,'  which  is  'even  more  important 
than  efficiency  and  expediency '  (p.  295).  Thus,  while  at  first  Mr. 
Briffault's  ethics  seem  to  be  the  antithesis  of  Kant's,  as  being  based  not 
upon  the  good  will  but  upon  the  results  obtained,  we  come  back  to  what 
is  expressly  called  (p.  296)  '  the  categorical  imperative  of  justice '.  '  It  is 
largely  because  of  the  vigour  of  the  forces  of  moral  protest  in  periods  of 
high  culture  that  all  their  abuses  and  corruptions  stand  pilloried  in  the 
fierce  light  of  denunciation  '  (p.  311).  This  is  no  doubt  quite  true.  '  Views 
and  opinions  are  the  only  ethically  significant,  the  only  moral  and  immoral 
things'  (p.  322).  'Our  morality  has  improved  because  our  intellectual 
development  and  rationality  have  advanced  '  (p.  325).  The  perversion 
which  he  finds  in  our  traditional  Christian  ethics  he  traces  to  the  stress 
laid  by  Stoics  and  Epicureans  on  the  formation  of  individual  character,  the 
consequence  of  which  is  that  '  the  basal  function  of  all  morality  becomes 
inverted;  it  actually  behoves  to  "resist  not  evil"'  (p.  332).  It  is  per- 
haps somewhat  surprising  to  find  that  with  these  opinions  Mr.  Briffault  is 
not  an  unbeliever  in  immortality. 

There  is  a  certain  nobility  in  Mr.  Briffault's  outlook  and,  if  one  is  dis- 
satisfied with  what  may  seem  a  one-sided  conception  of  morality,  there  is 
nowadays  so  much  justification  for  calling  attention  to  the  importance  of 
reason  in  life  that  one  may  easily  excuse  him  for  failing  to  solve  so  difficult 
a  problem  as  that  of  the  relation  of  our  moral  consciousness  to  the 
scientific  view  of  the  world.  On  the  principle  on  which  Kant  made  a 
practice  of  reading  books  which  aimed  at  disproving  the  reality  of  the 
three  great  objects  of  faith  while  neglecting  those  which  aimed  at  proving 
it,  some  of  us  who  are  less  content  than  Mr.  Briffault  to  part  company 
with  the  tradition  of  Christendom  may  yet  find  his  pages  more  profitable 
than  many,  more  balanced  and  more  scholarly,  written  in  support  of  that 
tradition. 

C.  C.  J.  W. 


Die    Religion    der    Vernunft    aus    den    Quellen    des    Judenthums.     By 
HERMANN  COHEN.    Leipzig  :  Gustav  Fock,  1919.     Pp.  iv,  629. 

This  massive  book  was  the  last  preoccupation  of  the  well-known  philo- 
sopher who,  along  with  Natorp,  has  for  many  years  led  the  so-called 
"  Marburg  school  ".  One  of  its  aims— and  this  alone  concerns  the  readers 
of  this  journal — may  be  said  to  be  the  detailed  transposition  of  Hebrew 
religious  thought  (the  general  results  of  modern  criticism  being  accepted) 
into  the  terms  of  pure  dialectic.  What  we  really  have  is  a  kind  of  allegor- 
ising treatment  of  Old  Testament  ideas  and  history,  only  in  this  case 
the  allegorical  method  yields,  not  religious  truths  or  moral  lessons,  but 
logical  values. 

It  is  reason,  we  are  told,  which  as  the  source  and  organ  of  conceptions 
first  creates  the  idea  of  religion  ;  for  reason  is  by  no  means  exhausted  in 
science  and  philosophy.  Like  those  other  disciplines,  religion,  in  so  far 
as  it  consists  of  and  rests  upon  .conceptions,  must  derive  ultimately  from 
reason.  And  when  Judaism  is  properly  construed,  it  can  be  shown  to 
contain,  as  no  other  faith  does,  the  purely  rational  religion.  The  course  of 
its  development  unfolds  the  creative  work  of  reason  in  the  sphere  of  das 
Heilige.  There  we  see  religion  displaying  itself  as  a  universal  function  of 
the  human  spirit.  As  the  Greeks  lit  upon  the  right  method  in  science,  so 
did  the  Hebrews  in  an  even  more  important  realm  of  life.  "  We  have  to 


228  NEW   BOOKS. 

investigate,  in  the  sources  of  Judaism,  the  deepest  philosophical  motives  by 
and  in  which  the  religion  of  reason  is  actualised.  And  we  shall  have  to 
note  that  this  elemental  force  of  reason  began  to  stir,  not  merely  in  the 
later  history  of  Judaism,  when  Greek  influences  were  at  work,  but  in  the 
very  earliest  thoughts  of  Judaism.  There  already  we  find  bonds  connect- 
ing the  Jewish  mind  with  philosophic  reason.  .  .  .  The  religion  of  reason 
imparts  to  the  sources  of  Judaism  its  original,  natural,  human  connexion 
with  philosophical  speculation,  and  is  no  more  imitated  from  Greece  than 
it  is  borrowed."  Perhaps  it  would  not  be  unfair  to  compare  this  with 
Hegel's  construction,  but  it  is  Hegelian  philosophy  of  religion  covering  and 
interpreting  not  all  the  great  faiths  but  solely  the  Hebrew  evolution. 

Everywhere  reason  stands  for  rule  or  norm,  hence  the  religion  of  reason  is 
fundamentally  determined  by  law.  Legality  is  the  very  mark  of  the  pious 
life.  Idolatry  must  be  eradicated,  and  there  is  no  fanaticism  whatever  in 
saying  so. 

But  does  religion  have  any  real  place  or  meaning  over  against  morality  ? 
Certainly  for  the  Jewish  mind  the  two  things  never  could  fall  apart. 
Reason  contains  the  principle  of  the  good,  by  which  morality  is  determined  ; 
it  also  contains  the  principles  of  monotheism.  But  the  distinction  between 
the  two,  which  is  as  real  as  the  kinship,  lies  in  this,  that  religion  discovers 
to  me  my  neighbour.  It  reveals  the  individual  "thou"  confronting  the 
"I,"  while  ethics  only  regards  the  individual  in  his  connexion  with 
humanity  as  a  whole.  Sympathy  with  pain  is  the  secret  ;  it  really  is  the 
point  at  which  religion  emerges  from  morality,  and  there  arises  a  new 
order  of  experience.  But  sin  as  well  as  pain  is  an  evil  with  revealing 
virtue  ;  and  it  is  just  because  he  discovered  man  to  himself  through  sin 
that  Ezekiel — a  true  parallel  to  the  ethical  Socrates — may  be  called  the 
founder  of  religion  proper. 

Cohen,  so  far  as  I  can  gather,  appears  to  think  of  God  pretty  much  as 
Arnold  did — a  tendency  in  things,  not  ourselves,  making  for  righteousness. 
Perhaps  we  might  define  God,  in  his  sense,  as  the  symbol  of  the  assured 
triumph  of  the  moral  ideal.  But  little  is  said  about  personal  fellowship, 
and  we  are  probably  not  unjust  if  we  conclude  that  what  he  offers  is  religion 
within  the  bounds  of  humanity.  The  unity  and  uniqueness  of  God  is  the 
all-commanding  thought  of  Judaism  ;  God  alone  is  true  being,  and  panthe- 
ism is  not  a  religion  at  all.  The  following  is  a  characteristic  passage  : 
"  The  uniqueness  (of  God)  signifies  also  the  distinction  between  being  and 
existence  (Daseiri).  And  this  distinction  brings  out  admirably  the  share 
which  reason  has  in  monotheism.  For  existence  is  witnessed  to  by  the 
senses,  by  perception.  On  the  other  hand  it  is  reason — in  contradiction 
to  the  senses  which  lends  reality  to  the  existence — that  discovers  super- 
sensible being,  lifts  the  supersensible  to  the  level  of  being,  singles  it  out 
as  being."  Because  God  is  unique,  He  is  unchangeable  as  well,  and  there 
can  be  no  mediation  between  Him  and  natural  existence.  This  condemns 
the  idea  of  the  Logos. 

For  our  present  purpose  we  need  go  no  further.  Especially  in  the 
earlier  part  of  the  book,  an  indefatigable  effort  is  made  to  work  out  the 
dialectical  equivalent  of  each  element  in  Hebrew  theology.  Thus  the 
logical  value  of  "  chaos  "  is  estimated  carefully.  There  is  something  nobly 
unbending  in  the  writer's  attitude,  and  many  good  things  are  said  by  the 
way,  but  the  enterprise  as  a  whole  seems  to  me  essentially  fruitless. 
Religion  is  not  in  any  sense  a  mystical  or  a  priori  logic.  Hebrew  roots  and 
words  are  not  in  fact  charged  with  a  profound  unconscious  theory  of  know- 
ledge, which  when  spelt  out  proves  to  be  an  anticipation  of  a  difficult 
nineteenth-century  system  of  philosophy. 

But  it  is  a  piquant  thought  that  the  Jewish  mind,  so  often  said  (I 
believe  wrongly)  to  have  contributed  in  its  Old  Testament  stage  little  or 


NEW  BOOKS.  229 

nothing  to  philosophy,  should  now  be  made  the  source  par  excellence  of 
rational  religion. 

The  Index,  which  is  specially  full,  extends  to  over  80  pages.  But  mis- 
prints are  lamentably  common. 

H.  R.  MACKINTOSH. 

Studies  in  Christian  Philosophy :  The  Boyle  Lectures,  1920.     By  W.  R. 
MATTHEWS,  M.A.,  B.D.     London  :  Macmillan,  &  Co.,  1920.     Pp.  228. 

IF  this  book  does  not  make  any  material  advance  upon  the  presentations 
of  theistic  argument  recently  put  forward  by  Profs.  Ward,  Pringle-Pattison 
and  Sorley,  it  may  be  said  to  carry  on  that  argument  on  the  lines  which 
the  best  forthcoming  theistic  philosophy  have  laid  down.  The  promise, 
contained  in  its  title,  to  discuss  the  distinctively  Christian  type  of  theism, 
is  but  scantily  fulfilled  ;  but  as  further  courses  of  Boyle  Lectures  are  to  be 
delivered  by  the  author,  we  may  expect  the  completion  of  his  purpose  in  a 
later  volume. 

The  present  work  on  ethical  theism  may  be  recommended  to  readers  of 
MIND  because,  unlike  some  essays  in  theological  apologetic,  it  does  not  set 
out  from  presuppositions  such  as  the  philosopher  would  be  inclined  to 
reject  as  groundless.  Its  writer  eschews  the  various  short  cuts  to  the 
establishment  of  theism  which  assume  what  is  called  '  the  validity  of 
religious  experience,'  and  the  familiar  attempts  to  avoid  in  one  way  or 
another  the  final  appeal  to  reason.  As  against  the  view  that  theology  is 
but  the  formulation  of  religious  experience,  he  holds  that  there  is  no  such 
thing  as  religious  experience  that  is  prior  to  the  fashioning  of  theological 
ideas,  and  that  whatever  is  sui  generis  in  religious  experience  is  to  be 
sought,  not  in  the  affective  and  conational  elements  which  such  experience 
contains,  but  in  the  ideas  which  are  employed  to  colligate  them  and  to 
assign  them  a  causal  explanation.  From  this  view  it  follows  that  theology 
involves  dogma  or  metaphysics  ;  and  it  is  the  tenability  of  such  metaphysic 
with  which  philosophy  of  religion  should  be  primarily,  if  not  solely, 
concerned. 

The  author  further  recognises  that  in  this  cognitional  aspect,  theology 
is  a  matter  of  belief,  not  of  knowledge  :  of  probability,  not  of  implication 
or  deinonstrability.  And,  in  this  connexion,  he  might  perhaps  have 
insisted  more  plainly  that  the  theist  can  afford  to  make  this  confession 
without  qualms  now  that  it  has  come  to  be  generally  recognised  that  all 
our  scientific  knowledge  of  the  world  presupposes  the  inductive  hypothesis 
and  the  venture  of  faith.  The  most  that  can  be  expected  from  theism  is 
thus  a  reasonable  ground  for  its  belief,  i.e.,  a  basis  in  such  partial  knowledge 
as  we  think  we  have  :  and  any  philosophy  concerned  to  repudiate  theism 
must  be  in  the  same  case.  Arguing,  as  I  understand  him,  on  these  lines, 
Mr.  Matthews  proceeds  to  maintain  that  theism  is  to-day  a  '  live  option, ' 
and  to  compare  its i reasonableness,  as  an  interpretation  of  the  world,  with 
that  of  other  current  alternatives  such  as  absolutism,  naturalism  and 
pluralism.  His  examination  of  thase  rival  options  is  but  cursory  ;  but  if 
it  dismisses  them  somewhat  facilely  on  that  account,  it  at  any  rate  serves 
to  exhibit  clearly  the  characteristics  of  theism.  The  same  purpose  is 
furthered  by  the  lectures  on  divine  personality  and  the  idea  of  creation. 
But  the  most  important  link  in  the  chain  of  theistic  argument,  which  as  a 
whole  one  may  best  describe  as  cumulatively  teleological,  is  supplied  by 
considerations  concerning  human  morality.  Mr.  Matthews  assigns  a 
prominent  position  to  arguments  based  on  such  considerations  ;  but  he 
aims  at  more  than  deriving  from  them  additional  strength  for  a  cumulative 
teleology.  As  I  have  already  offered  criticism  of  these  several  moral  argu- 
ments in  another  review,  I  will  here  say  no  more  than  that  none  of  the 


230  NEW  BOOKS. 

various  attempts  that  have  been  made  to  show  that  theism  is  the  necessary 
presupposition  of  the  objectivity  of  moral  truths  or  of  ethical  ideals  seems 
to  me  to  be  free  from  fallacy,  and  that  the  author's  argumentation,  like 
that  of  other  recent  defenders  of  theism,  is  weaker  rather  than  stronger 
for  trying  to  extract  more  evidence  for  theism  from  the  sphere  of  values 
than  is  furnished  by  the  fact  that  the  world  is  so  constituted  as  to  be 
instrumental  to  the  acquisition  of  the  moral  status  and  to  moral  progress. 
The  theist  of  to-day  is  indeed  seldom,  if  ever,  content  with  this  modicum 
of  '  moral  proof  '  ;  but  I  think  that  his  valour,  in  fighting  so  lightly  armed, 
would  prove  the  better  part  of  his  discretion. 

F.  R.  TENNANT. 

Pantheism  and  the  Value  of  Life,  with  Special  Reference  to  Indian 
Philosophy.  By  W.  S.  URQUHART,  M.  A.,  D.Phil.  London :  Epworth 
Press,  1919.  Pp.  732. 

This  work  was  originally  submitted  as  a  thesis  for  the  degree  of  D.Phil,  of 
Aberdeen  University.  It  is  divided  into  three  books  and  an  Introduction 
of  fifty-four  pages.  Book  I.  (pp.  57-514)*  deals  with  Pantheism  and  the 
Value  of  Life  in  Indian  Philosophy.  Book  II.  (pp.  515-580)  treats  of 
Pantheism  in  Western  Philosophy.  Book  III.  is  devoted  to  recapitulation 
and  generalisation.  The  author  says  in  the  preface,  "  I  should  esteem  it  a 
favour  if  attention  were  mainly  directed  to  the  Introduction  and  Books  I. 
and  III,  very  specially  to  Book  I.  which  deals  exclusively  with  Indian 
Philosophy".  On  the  next  page  of  the  preface  he  tells  us  the  object 
which  he  has  in  view  in  writing  this  work  :  "  At  times  there  seems  to 
have  been  a  slight  tendency  both  to  underestimate  the  value  of  Western 
philosophical  and  religious  contribution  and  to  overlook  certain  deficiencies 
in  Indian  speculation  which  near  and  constant  contact  with  the  peoples  of 
India  makes  abundantly  evident.  My  own  opinion  is  that  a  radical  trans- 
formation of  Indian  thought  will  be  necessary  if  India  is  to  advance 
mentally,  morally,  and  religiously,  and  my  main  object  in  this  discussion 
is  to  show,  with,  I  hope,  all  due  and  sympathetic  appreciation  of  the  im- 
mense value  of  Indian  philosophy,  the  necessity  for  this  transformation." 
In  accordance  with  the  author's  request  I  shall  limit  myself  to  the  main 
part  of  his  work  which  deals  with  Indian  philosophy. 

The  fundamental  position  of  Pantheism  is  defined  by  Prof.  Urquhart  as 
"  the  double  assertion  that  God  is  all  that  is  and  that  there  cannot  be  any- 
thing but  God".  The  effect  of  Pantheism  on  the  value  of  life  is  to  be 
judged  by  deciding  whether  it  leads  to  pessimism  or  optimism.  True 
optimism  is  defined  "  as  that  attitude  of  mind  which,  in  full  consciousness 
of  the  exact  state  of  things  in  the  world,  holds  to  the  belief  that  the 
highest  values  are  being  and  will  be  realised  ".  Pessimism  in  its  positive 
aspect  is  regarded  as  the  belief  that  the  process  of  the  world  is  towards 
evil  and  towards  pain,  and  in  its  negative  aspect  as  indifference  to  the  need 
of  progress  or  the  denial  of  its  possibility  ;  and  these  two  aspects  are  so 
closely  related  that  the  latter  type  often  leads  to  the  former. 

In  dealing  with  the  Vedic  religion,  Prof.  Urquhart  holds  that  the  Vedic 
people  believed  that  the  hidden  forces  of  the  world  were  like  a  fluid  and  a 
semi-material  reality  which  the  worshipper  by  means  of  certain  rites  and 
incantations  may  participate  in  and  thus  obtain  divine  power  through  a 
process  of  physical  absorption.  This  is  indeed  a  very  curious  doctrine  and 
Prof.  Urquhart  does  not  tell  us  on  what  authority  he  considers  this  as  a 
fundamental  Vedic  doctrine.  We  know  that  the  Vedic  people  believed  in 
the  magical  force  of  sacrifices,  but  we  are  not  aware  that  this  was  a  semi- 
material  fluid  in  which  the  worshipper  participated.  In  a  curious  way  he 
associates  this  with  an  ascetic  tinge  and  discovers  the  germ  of  the  negative 


NEW  BOOKS.  231 

idea  which  permeates  the  whole  of  Indian  philosophy.  I  do  not  further 
find  it  easy  to  agree  with  him  in  his  view  that  at  the  root  of  the  Upanishad 
quest,  there  was  any  dark  background,  or  that  it  was  actuated  by  the  grow- 
ing consciousness  of  the  need  of  deliverance.  So  far  as  I  have  understood 
the  Upanishads,  I  have  found  them  characterised  by  an  absorbing  percep- 
tion of  truth  and  the  enthusiasm  and  gladness  of  this  discovery.  It  never 
appeared  to  me  that  the  Upanishads  had  any  pessimistic  tinge.  All 
through  them  is  found  a  gust  of  joy  and  truth.  It  would  have  been  well  if 
each  of  the  chapters  of  this  book  could  be  even  briefly  discussed,  but  space 
is  too  limited  and  it  is  impossible  to  do  justice  to  a  book  of  over  seven 
hundred  pages  in  such  a  short  notice.  But  we  must  say  that  it  is  wrong 
to  assert  that  Ved:intism  has  led  to  pessimism.  It  appears  almost  certain 
that  pessimism  crept  into  Hindu  thought  from  Buddhism,  which  regarded 
sorrow,  the  cause  of  sorrow,  the  destruction  of  sorrow,  and  the  cause  of  its 
destruction  as  the  Four  Noble  Truths.  Most  of  the  later  Indian  systems 
of  philosophy  accepted  it  tacitly  or  expressly.  It  is  also  wrong  to  think 
that  Vedantism  was  typical  of  Indian  philosophy,  for  all  the  other  systems 
such  as  that  of  the  Jains,  the  Samkhya,  Yoga,  Nyaya,  Vaigeshika, 
Mlmamsa,  or  the  later  Vishnuite  schools  of  Yamuna,  Ramanuja,  Madhva, 
Nimbarka,  Baladeva,  etc.,  are  either  dualistic  or  pluralistic,  and  in  this 
sense  Vedantism  may  be  regarded  rather  as  an  exception  than  as  the 
model.  The  idea  that  the  world  is  sorrowful  was  shared  more  or  less 
by  all  these  schools  of  thought,  and  it  is  extremely  unfair  to  associate  it 
particularly  with  Vedantism.  Since  the  time  of  Buddhism  this  idea  ex- 
pressed itself  as  an  attitude  of  the  Indian  mind,  and  no  particular  system 
of  thought  can  be  made  responsible.  It  must  also  be  said  that  of  all  the 
systems,  Vedantism  is  least  pessimistic  ;  nowhere  in  the  Vedanta  literature 
is  this  sorrowful  aspect  of  the  world  emphasised  half  as  much  as  in  the 
pluralistic  system  of  Samkhya  Yoga.  The  whole  ambition  of  Vedanta  is 
to  prove  that  this  world  has  only  a  secondary,  phenomenal,  and  changeful 
existence,  and  that  the  ultimate  truth  is  pure  consciousness,  which  is  also 
pure  bliss.  Vedantism  did  not  hold  that  pain  and  sorrow  did  not  exist  at 
all ;  but  it  held  that  it  had  only  a  secondary  phenomenal  existence,  and 
must  be  considered  as  illusory  when  compared  with  the  ultimate  reality  ; 
and  it  also  believed  that  we  were  progressing  towards  the  attainment  of 
this  highest  goal  and  that  we  should  all  attain  it.  According  to  Prof. 
Urquhart's  definition  of  optimism  we  should  like  to  call  Vedantism 
optimism  and  not  pessimism. 

S.  N.  DASGUPTA. 

Indian  Logic  and  Atomism  :  An  Exposition  of  the  Nydya  and  Vaipesika 
Systems.  By  ARTHUR  BERRIED  ALE  KEITH,  D.C.L.,  D.Litt.  Oxford: 
Clarendon  Press,  1921.  Pp.  291. 

Prof.  Keith's  book  will  be  warmly  welcomed  by  all  who  are  interested  in 
the  study  of  Indian  philosophy.  It  belongs  to  a  new  era  of  research  on 
Indian  philosophy,  in  which  elementary  compendiums  are  not  taken  as  the 
main  guides  for  the  understanding  of  a  system  of  thought.  Many  writers 
have  written  on  the  Nyfiya  system,  but  in  most  cases,  with  some  notable 
exceptions  such  as  the  Sadholal  Lectures  by  Dr.  Ganganath  Jha,  or  the 
Indian  Logic  by  the  late  Dr.  Vidyabhushana,  they  limited  themselves  to 
the  information  that  could  be  gleaned  from  such  compendiums  as  Bhas- 
hapariccheda,  Tarkasangraha  or  the  SaptapadarthI,  which  though  good  in 
themselves  are  quite  insufficient  for  explaining  the  position  of  Nyaya  as  a 
system  of  philosophy.  The  great  merit  of  Prof.  Keith's  work  is  that  he 
has  based  his  exposition  on  the  main  works  of  the  Nyaya- Vaigeshika  litera- 
ture. There  may  be  differences  of  opinion,  with  regard  to  the  absolute 


232  NEW  BOOKS. 

correctness  or  lucidity  of  his  interpretation,  but  that  does  not  affect  the 
value  and  honesty  of  the  work  that  he  has  executed.  Those  who  are  ac- 
quainted with  the  difficulty  and  abstruseness  of  Indian  philosophical  litera 
ture  will,  I  think,  freely  admit  that  it  is  only  by  a  series  of  such  honest 
attempts  that  we  can  hope  correctly  to  interpret  Indian  thought  and 
adjudge  its  true  value  and  relation  to  modern  philosophical  thought.  Prof. 
Keith's  scholarly  work  has  certainly  advanced  the  course  of  Nyaya  studies 
one  step  further. 

The  book  is  in  two  parts.  The  first  contains  only  forty-one  pages,  and 
gives  an  account  of  the  Nyaya-Vai9eshika  literature  and  discusses  certain 
historical  questions  connected  with  the  subject.  The  second  part  is  in  two 
divisions,  on  epistemology  and  metaphysics.  The  part  on  epistemology  is 
divided  into  six  sections,  Knowledge  and  Error,  Perception,  Inference, 
Logical  Errors,  Nature  and  Authority  of  Speech,  and  Dialectical  Categories. 
The  part  on  metaphysics  deals  with  Ontology,  Philosophy  of  Nature,  Philo- 
sophy of  Spirit,  and  the  Existence  and  Nature  of  God.  In  the  section  on 
knowledge  and  error  Prof.  Keith  considers  the  different  Indian  views  on 
the  nature  of  knowledge,  and  contrasts  them  with  the  Nyaya  view  that 
correct  apprehension  may  briefly  be  described  as  that  which  attributes  to 
an  object  with  a  certain  attribute  the  corresponding  characteristic,  while 
false  apprehension  is  one  which  ascribes  a  characteristic  to  a  thing  which 
has  not  the  corresponding  attribute.  In  the  next  section  he  gives  us  the 
Nyaya  justification  of  the  four  means  of  proof,  perception,  inference,  ana- 
logical judgment,  and  verbal  knowledge,  as  against  other  views  on  the 
subject.  He  gives  us  the  Nyaya  principle  of  the  division  of  means  of  proof 
and  says,  "  Means  of  proof,  in  this  view,  is  that  which  is  always  accompanied 
by  true  knowledge  and  at  the  same  time  is  not  disjoined  from  the  appro- 
priate organs  or  from  the  seat  of  consciousness,  i.e.,  the  soul.  .  .  .  The 
true  sense  of  pramana  thus  appears  not  as  a  mere  instrument  of  proof,  but 
the  mode  in  which  the  instrument  is  used,  the  process  by  which  the  know- 
ledge appropriate  to  each  means  of  proof  is  arrived  at."  The  third  section 
deals  with  error,  which  "  consists  in  having  the  knowledge  of  an  object  as 
possessed  of  attributes  which  are  not  in  accord  with  the  real  nature  of  the 
thing  ".  In  his  chapter  on  perception  he  starts  with  Gautama's  definition 
of  it  as  "  knowledge  which  arises  from  the  contact  of  sense  and  organ,  when 
not  subject  to  error,  when  not  requiring  further  determination  and  de- 
finite," and  discusses  its  relation  with  Dignaga  and  Dharmakirtti's  definitions 
of  perception  as  "  correct  knowledge  free  from  determination  by  imagina- 
tion," and  he  then  deals  with  the  different  kinds  of  sense-contact  necessary 
for  perception  and  its  stages  as  indeterminate  and  determinate.  In  the 
subsequent i  chapters  he  deals  with  inference  and  the  fallacies,  and  discusses 
the  questions  of  Pra^astapada's  debt  to  Dignaga.  In  the  part  dealing  with 
metaphysics  he  treats  of  the  Vaigeshika  categories  of  substance,  quality, 
activity,  generality,  particularity,  and  inherence,  the  doctrine  of  cause  and 
effect  and  of  negation,  and  the  atomic  theory,  soul,  mind  and  body,  and  the 
proofs  of  the  existence  of  God. 

I  do  not,  however,  think  that  Prof.  Keith  has  in  all  places  correctly  in- 
terpreted the  Nyaya  view.  It  would  have  been  profitable  to  have  discussed 
some  of  these  here  but  space  is  too  limited.  I  shall,  however,  give  one  or 
two  examples.  On  page  69  Prof .  Keith  says,  "The  self  is  all-pervading 
consciousness  .  .  .  ,"  but  this  is  inexact,  for  according  to  Nyaya,  the  self  is 
all-pervading,  but  it  is  not  consciousness.  Consciousness  is  associated  with 
it  as  a  result  of  suitable  collocations.  Thus  the  Nyayaman  jarl  says  (p.  432)  : 
"  The  dtman  is  conscious  through  association  with  consciousness  (cit). 
We  do  not  regard  anything  as  consciousness  other  than  the  manifestation 
of  objects."  Again  on  page  72  he  describes  indeterminate  perception  as 
"that  which  gives  the  bare  knowledge  of  the  class- character  of  the  object  ". 


NEW  BOOKS.  233 

Whatever  may  be  the  case  with  Gange§a,  this  is  not  the  early  Nyaya  view, 
'which  held  that  also  particulars  were  perceived  at  the  first  stage.     Tat- 
paryyatika,  page  91  ;  Nyayamanjari,  page  95  ;  Nyayakandali,  page  189. 

S.  N.  DASGUPTA. 

The  Mneme.     By  R.  SEMON.      Translated  by  L.  SIMON.      London  :   G^ 
Allen  &  Unwin,  Ltd.,  1921.    Pp.  304. 

Most  biologists  are  inclined  to  interpret  the  more  developed  and  more 
differentiated  manifestations  of  life  in  terms  of  the  less  developed  and 
less  differentiated.  They  would  describe  a  hen  as  a  modified  egg  rather 
than  an  egg  as  an  undeveloped  hen.  This  tendency  has  its  origin,  one 
suspects,  partly  in  the  belief  that  what  comes  first  in  time  comes  first  in 
logic  and  partly  in  an  analogy  with  the  physical  sciences,  where  the  aim  is 
to  describe  every  process  as  a  special  case  of  the  simplest  and  most 
general  laws.  The  analogy  with  physics  is  usually  misleading  and  the 
historical  argument  is  certainly  false.  Physiologists  as  a  rule  realise 
that,  if  you  want  to  understand  the  mechanism  of  life  processes,  it  is  best 
to  start  the  investigation  with  the  most  highly  specialised  and  differentiated 
organ  you  can  find,  something  such  as  a  muscle  or  a  nerve  that  has  been 
modified  to  perform  one  particular  function.  When  something  has  been 
elucidated  in  this  case  the  knowledge  is  likely  to  throw  light  on  the  more 
difficult  cases  of  processes  in  unspecialised  and  undifferentiated  tissues, 
whose  apparent  structural  simplicity  conceals  a  great  complexity  of 
function.  It  was  long  believed  that  a  study  of  the  Central  Nervous 
System  would  solve  some  of  the  problems  of  psychology,  but  it  is  probably 
nearer  the  mark  to  say,  that  of  the  small  amount  of  light  that  has  been 
shed  on  nervous  functions  a  large  part  comes  from  psychology.  Nearly 
all  that  is  said  about  brain  processes  would  be  unintelligible  but  for  our 
introspective  knowledge  of  mental  processes. 

The  late  Prof.  Semon  seems  to  have  been  one  of  the  first  biologists  to 
realise  that  an  exclusive  study  of  the  primitive  life  processes  was  not 
likely  to  lead  anywhere,  and  to  suggest  that  what  we  know  of  the  most 
highly  developed  living  functions  might  help  us  to  understand  the  less 
developed.  He  attempted  to  raise  biological  speculation  above  the  futile 
wrangles  of  Mechanists  and  Vitalists,  Weismannists  and  Lamarckians  ;  to 
try  and  provide  a  little  bread  in  place  of  all  these  small  pebbles.  It  is  idle 
to  quarrel  with  the  details  of  his  exposition  of  his  views,  though  it  is  not 
difficult  to  do  so,  and  idle  to  cavil  at  his  barbarous  terminology  unless  we 
can  substitute  something  better.  What  we  certainly  ought  to  recognise  and 
to  lay  stress  on  is  his  general  outlook  on  the  classical  biological  problems. 
He  has  made  a  bold  attempt  to  provide  a  constructive  and  unifying  theory 
in  terms  of  which  we  can  regard  the  processes  of  reproduction,  growth  and 
development.  The  test  of  his  views  will  be  whether  the  facts  as  they 
accumulate  can  be  ordered  in  terms  of  his  theory  and  whether  the  theory 
bears  fruit  in  suggesting  fresh  methods  of  investigation.  Successful 
experiment  and  correct  observation  in  these  matters  is  so  difficult  that 
the  testing  of  a  general  theory  is  of  necessity  a  slow  business. 

We  all  of  us  know  how  past  experience  modifies  present  experience 
and  it  is  obvious  that  this  process  of  learning  by  experience  is  one  of  the 
salient  facts  about  our  mental  life.  We  also  know  that  we  can  observe  in 
all  living  creatures  physical  reactions  to  physical  stimuli  which  are  the 
analogues  of  our  mental  reactions  and  their  concomitants  in  our  own 
bodies.  Good  evolutionists  must  believe  that  minds  and  bodies  and 
particularly  minds  and  nervous  systems  have  grown  up  in  close  con- 
junction. Now  Semon  holds  that  this  process  of  memory  that  is  obviously 
characteristic  of  minds  and  brains  is  characteristic  of  all  living  cells  and 


234  NEW  BOOKS 

governs  all  their  relations  with  the  outside  world  and  with  one  another. 
In  particular  he  attributes  the  special  character  of  growth  and  inheritance 
and  the  evolution  of  species  to  this  process.  The  phenomena  of  growth 
and  reproduction  are  so  staggering  and  so  miraculous  that  it  hardly  seems 
fair  to  expect  any  theory  to  explain  them.  But  as  far  as  one  can  see 
Semon's  theory  does  fit  in  pretty  well  with  what  is  known  and  should 
stimulate  further  investigation. 

Only  a  short  time  ago,  when  Weismann's  influence  was  supreme,  it  was 
customary  to  believe  that  very  little  you  could  do  to  an  organism  would 
alter  the  germ  cells  in  any  way,  and  that  no  modification  to  the  organism 
could  modify  them  in  the  same  direction.  It  was  said  that  it  was  in- 
conceivable that  the  germ  cells  could  be  influenced  in  this  way  and  that 
the  experimental  evidence  was  all  against  it.  Since  the  days  of  Weismann, 
and  since  the  first  edition  of  this  book  even,  the  balance  of  evidence  has 
been  slowly  shifting  in  the  other  direction,  in  favour  of  the  possibility  of 
the  inheritance  of  acquired  characters.  As  might  be  expected,  it  is  only 
in  certain  ways  and  under  certain  conditions  that  the  germ  cells  can  be 
affected  in  the  right  way,  but  it  does  seem  to  happen.  This  is  really  a 
considerable  triumph  for  Semon's  views. 

The  orderly  and  inevitable  course  of  the  process  of  growth  is  at  present 
a  complete  mystery,  but  here  again  there  is  hope  that  Semon's  views  may 
shed  some  light.  Certainly  other  theories  have  shed  nothing  but  deeper 
shadow. 

Altogether  the  time  is  ripe  for  a  reasonable  consideration  of  Semon's 
theories.  As  they  have  not  apparently  received  much  notice  in  English- 
speaking  countries  the  appearance  of  this  clear  and  readable  translation 
seems  to  be  opportune. 

A.  D.  R. 

Especes  et  Variety's  d'  Intelligences,  Elements  de  Noologie.     By  FRAI^OIS 
MENTRE,  Docteur  es  Lettres.     Paris  :  Bossard,  1920.     Pp.  294. 

The  author,  who  in  his  work  on  Les  Generations  Sociales1  studied  the 
historical  influence  of  groupings  united  by  a  particular  mentality,  here,  with 
the  same  learning  and  suggestiveness,  is  working  towards  the  development 
of  a  science  which  shall  be,  KO  to  speak,  a  natural  history  of  the  species  or 
families  of  intelligences.  The  name  n oology  is  derived,  I  gather,  from 
Ampere  ;  but  the  author  traces  the  point  of  view  from  Pascal  downwards, 
principally  through  French  psychologists  and  critics.  (Ostwald  is  an 
exception,  and  I  suppose  also  Wechniakoff,  who  appears,  however,  to 
have  written  in  French.  I  regret  that  I  am  not  acquainted  with  his 
work.) 

The  researches,  which  are  traced  at  length,  tend  to  result  in  triple  classifi- 
cations. That  which  originates  with  Pascal  (p.  77),  and  is  practically 
repeated  by  Poincare  (p.  116),  and  Duhem  (p.  133),  summarised  p.  140 
— a  classification  of  savants  only — is  in  its  latest  form  (Duhem)  "  Esprits 
rigouteux,  esprits  amples,  esprits  justes  (Pascal's  esprits  de  finesse) "  ; 
which,  as  I  gather,  represent  respectively  the  capacity  for  rigorous  uni- 
linear deduction,  for  imaginative  intuition  from  a  conspectus  of  data,  e.g., 
of  figures  in  geometry  (the  "ample"  mind  is  also  "  feeble  "  ;  the  "rigor- 
ous "  mind  is  "strong"),  and  for  general  appreciation  in  matters  of 
feeling  which  adds  persuasiveness  to  abstract  reasoning.  After  further 
discussion,  in  which,  principally  on  the  authority  of  A.  Binet,  the 
"  praticien,"  evidently  a  favourite  with  the  writer,  is  added  to  the  list,  we 
have  an  elaborate  tabular  form  (p.  278)  which  gives  three  fundamental 

1  See  notice  in  New  Books,  MIND,  July,  1921. 


NEW   BOOKS.  235 

types  or  genera  of  Intelligences  ;  the  Praticien  (leading  example,  an 
extraordinarily  precocious  and  skilful  laboratory  assistant  described  by 
Binet),  the  Contemplatif  (Imagination  on  an  emotional  basis),  and  the 
Meditatif  (the  Scientific  mind).  The  two  latter  genera  absorb  Duhem's 
triple  division,  and  the  three  are  supplemented  by  a  number  of  hybrids, 
derivations,  and  deviations.  The  author  claims  a  practical  value  for  his 
science,  both  in  the  application  of  moral  rules  and  in  teaching.  In  both 
we  must  in  future  reckon  with  a  real  existence  of  different  types  and 
adjust  our  action  accordingly  (pp.  284-285  and  note).  A  long  review  might 
be  written  on  the  detailed  suggestions  drawn  from  many  great  writers, 
St.  Beuve,  Taine,  who  had  a  doctrine  of  a  faculte  maitresse  (p.  84)  which 
gives  the  mind  a  sort  of  spurious  unity,  Paulhan  and  others.  But  in  a 
limited  space  perhaps  the  best  thing  I  can  do  is  to  raise  a  question  of 
principle  which  affects  the  root  of  the  new  science. 

I  speak  with  the  utmost  diffidence  in  presence  of  so  profound  a  student 
and,  I  presume,  so  experienced  a  teacher,  as  the  author.  But  one  can 
give  only  what  one  has  ;  so  I  mention  my  difficulty.  I  do  not  doubt  that 
these  types  of  minds  are  found ;  nor  that  the  study  of  them  is  important. 
But  I  do  wonder  whether  the  idea  of  a  natural  history  of  species  or 
families  of  intelligences  (character  is  strictly  ruled  out)  is  philosophically 
sound.  A  member  of  a  natural  species,  including  its  psycho-physical 
endowment,  is  what  it  is,  and  though  it  changes  throughout  its  life,  yet 
its  life-history  is  almost  a  datum.  You  can  safely  co-ordinate  it  with 
others,  and  write  down  its  actual  affinities.  But  for  a  human  being  the 
corresponding  data  are  no  more  than  starting-points  for  the  intelligence. 
Intelligence  is  essentially  thought ;  and  thought  is,  in  principle,  in  relation 
with  the  entire  real  universe,  which  it  may  approach  from  any  starting- 
point,  and  you  cannot  tell  how  far  it  may  reach  therefrom.  Thus  you  get 
the  idea  of  a  normal  or  central  development,  in  which  all  sides  of  reality 
tend  to  assert  themselves,  and  the  beings  of  marked  species,  instead  of 
each  being  distinct  after  his  kind,  tend  to  unite  many  features,  on  pain 
of  appearing  defective.  Paulhan  roundly  says  there  are  no  natural  species 
of  intelligences  (p.  100) ;  Binet  says  his  model  praticien  is  incomplete  as 
a  mind  ;  the  author  protests  (p.  218  and  note).  Duhem  says  the  national 
spirit  is  not  traceable  in  the  greatest  minds  (Newton,  e.g.,  and  Gauss),  and 
it  is  in  ordinary  mentalities  that  you  get  monstrosities  "  tandis  que  les 
grands  genies  realisent  1'ideal  unique  du  genre  human"  (pp.  129,  130,  see 
the  author's  note,  which  points  out  that  this  idea  treats  mental  species  as 
deviations  round  a  uniform  ideal  type).  The  immense  faculty  of  adapta- 
tion shown  by  the  human  mind  as  it  goes  through  life,  e.g.,  in  adopting  a 
profession,  demonstrates  what  various  resources  are  common  to  intelligences 
as  such.  The  author's  ideal  species  is  the  pure  type ;  but  his  tabular 
form  shows  hardly  any  such.  And  of  the  antithetic  terms,  proposed  as 
titles  of  exclusive  types,  most  have  been  rejected  as  not  reciprocally 
exclusive.  The  species,  even  when  morbid,  are  only  cases  of  predominant 
features,  and  I  should  urge,  following  Duhem,  that  the  greatest  minds  are 
the  most  many-sided.  The  author's  account  of  Plato  would  not  lead  one  to 
surmise  that  a  great  critic  (Walter  Pater)  has  said  of  him  what  Gautier, 
as  the  author  reminds  us,  said  of  himself ;  that  he  was  one  for  whom  the 
external  world  really  existed  1.  I  doubt,  then,  the  whole  conception  of  pure 
natural  species  of  intelligences,  because  an  intelligence  has  open  to  it 
the  whole  reality,  it  is  always  in  a  high  degree  many-sided,  and  you  never 
can  tell  what  line  within  reality  it  may  pursue. 

BEENAED  BOSANQUET. 
1  Pater  says  "  visible,"  Plato  and  Platonism,  p.  114. 


236  NEW   BOOKS. 

The  Essentials  of  Mental  Measurement.  By  WILLIAM  BROWN  and  GODFREY 
H.  THOMSON.  Cambridge  University  Press.  Pp.  viii  +  216.  21s. 
net. 

This  is  a  new  and  greatly  enlarged  edition  of  a  book  by  Dr.  William 
Brown,  published  in  1911,  which  was  again  an  expansion  of  a  booklet 
reviewed  by  the  present  writer  in  MIND,  July,  1911.  The  new  chapters, 
writes  Dr.  Brown,  are  wholly  the  work  of  Dr.  Thomson.  They  deal  with 
the  Elementary  Theory  of  Probability,  Skewness  and  Heterogeneity  in 
Psychophysical  data,  the  Influence  of  Selection,  the  Theory  of  General 
Ability  and  a  Sampling  Theory  of  Ability. 

These  additions,  and  other  revisions,  greatly  enhance  the  value  of  the 
book,  making  it  a  much  more  complete  account  of  recent  developments 
in  the  application  of  mathematical  calculations  to  the  study  of  mental 
abilities  and  mental  performance.  The  elementary  theory  of  probability, 
and  the  methods  employed  in  various  ways  of  measuring  scatter,  reliability, 
etc.,  are  discussed  with  admirable  clearness. 

The  chief  interest  in  the  book  to  psychologists  however  will  probably 
lie  in  the  extended  treatment  of  correlation  in  Part  II.  and  especially  in 
the  full  and  lively  discussion  of  the  controversy  which  has  been  centred 
round  the  problems  of  the  hierarchy  of  correlation  coefficients,  and  the 
proof  through  that  of  a  "  general  factor  "  in  all  mental  performances. 

The  controversy,  though  strenuous  and  emphatic  enough  in  its  criticism 
of  Prof.  Spearman's  position,  is  preceded  in  the  preface  by  a  warm  acknow- 
ledgment of  the  "  epoch-making  "  significance  of  Spearman's  work  in 
the  application  of  correlation  to  psychology.  Dr.  Thomson  assails,  on 
several  grounds,  Spearman's  view  that  the  presence  of  a  general  factor  is 
proved  by  the  hierarchy  shown  by  sets  of  correlation  coefficients.  He 
urges  that  while  Spearman  quite  rightly  asserts  that  a  general  factor  would 
produce  a  hierarchical  order  among  coefficients,  he  has  no  right  to  reverse 
the  argument  and  conclude  that  the  presence  of  hierarchical  order  proves 
the  existence  of  a  general  factor.  Also,  that  while  a  series  of  group  factors 
may  give  no  hierarchy,  yet  they  will  do  so  if  the  group  factors  overlap. 
And  in  support  of  the  view  that  the  matter  is  more  complicated  than  the 
theory  of  one  general  ability  factor  would  suggest,  he  points  to  other  wide- 
spread factors  which  others  claim  to  have  found,  viz.,  Maxwell  Garnett's 
"  cleverness  and  purpose  "  factor  and  E.  Webb's  "  persistence  of  motives  " 
factor. 

Furthermore  Dr.  Thomson  has  produced  a  series  of  correlation  of 
coefficients  by  experiments  with  dice,  with  conditions  corresponding  to 
group  factors,  the  arrangement  of  the  group  factors  being  decided  by  the 
chance  drawing  of  cards  from  a  pack.  And  these  correlation  coefficients 
gave  an  almost  perfect  hierarchical  order. 

Dr.  Thomson  even  goes  so  far  as  to  say  that  a  hierarchy  is  the  "  natural  " 
relation  among  correlation  coefficients  on  any  theory  whatever  of  the 
cause  of  the  correlation,  though,  I  take  it,  he  would  not  say  this  in 
reference  to  correlations  of  orders  arranged  on  the  mere  basis  of  chance 
draws,  without  even  group  factors  being  involved.1 

Dr.  Thomson  also  uses  his  theory  of  groups  of  mental  factors  to  explain 
apparent  "  general  ability  ".  The  usual  absence  of  a  tranference  of  train- 
ing effects  from  one  activity  to  another  activity  (except  to  a  very  similar 
one)  he  explains  by  suggesting  that  this  specific  improvement  in  a  given 

1  Dr.  Thomson's  reply  to  an  inquiry  of  mine  on  this  point  confirms  my 
impression  that  he  did  not  mean  to  suggest,  as  he  has  been  understood  to 
do  by  another  reviewer,  that  mere  chance  would  produce  a  hierarchy  in 
the  absence  of  all  definite  factors  causing  correlation. 


NEW  BOOKS.  237 

activity  is  due  largely  to  improved  "  team  "  work  among  the  elements  of 
the  group,  and  that  when  another  group  is  formed  partially  of  the  same 
factors,  the  improved  co-ordination  is  lost,  just  as,  when  members  of  a  foot- 
ball team  which  has  improved  as  a  team  are  scattered  among  several  teams, 
the  value  of  the  team  work  training  is  largely  lost. 

The  present  reviewer  would  not  presume  to  decide  the  problems  of  higher 
mathematics  at  issue  between  Profs.  Spearman  and  Thomson.  Indeed  it 
is  evident  that  even  the  expert  mathematician  must  walk  warily  in  inter- 
preting correlations.  It  may  be  added,  however,  that  from  the  psycho- 
logical point  of  view  it  unhappily  still  remains  true,  as  the  present 
reviewer  wrote  in  the  review  of  Dr.  Brown's  original  booklet,  that  "the 
doubtful  accuracy  of  mathematical  formula  is  scarcely  more  serious  to 
the  statistician  than  the  vagueness  and  variability  which  still  remain  in 
the  way  of  measuring  some  of  the  capacities  among  which  correlations  are 
sought".  Mental  tests  have  been  vastly  developed  and  systematised 
since  1911,  but  variations  in  the  modes  of  application  and  in  the  inter- 
pretation of  results  are  still  responsible  for  considerable  variations  in 
correlation  coefficients  obtained  by  different  workers. 

That  is,  however,  not  the  main  concern  of  our  authors.  To  the  treat- 
ment of  the  problems  involved  in  advancing  the  mathematical  aspect  of 
the  work  and  in  the  co-ordination  of  mathematical  results  with  psycho- 
logical theory,  they  have  in  this  book  made  a  very  notable  contribution. 

A  very  extensive  bibliography  is  added. 

C.  W.  VALENTINE. 


La  Musique  et  la  vie  Interieure  :  Essai  d'une  Histoire  Psychologique  de 
Vart  Musical.  Par  LUCIEN  BOURGUES  et  ALEXANDRE  DENEREAZ. 
Paris  VI.,  Alcan,  1921.  Pp.  xi,  586.  (7J  x  10  in.)  50  francs  net. 

This  large  work  is  illustrated  with  983  musical  examples,  eighteen  figures, 
nineteen  tables  showing  the  musical  influence  of  previous  composers  upon 
a  given  great  master  and  his  influence  upon  his  successors,  and  a  plate 
giving  the  dynamogenic  curves  of  a  number  of  pieces  of  music  as  the 
authors  feel  them.  It  could  hardly  be  called  an  indispensable  work,  but 
it  is  certainly  one  that  every  serious  student  of  music  should  see.  Intimate 
knowledge  and  enthusiastic  love  of  music  are  evident  on  every  page,  and 
the  style  is  as  musical  as  the  words  of  discursive  thought  may  be.  The 
writers'  minds  are  evidently  permeated  with  the  problems  of  music  and 
they  are  eager  to  further  their  solution. 

But  the  science  they  have  at  their  command  is  quite  inadequate  for  the 
task.  In  character  it  is  post-Helmholtzian,  as  the  constant  recourse  to 
harmonics  shows,  but  it  is  nothing  more.  It  is  the  '  science  '  of  music  that  a 
student  <of  twenty  to  fifty  years  ago  might  have  imbibed  at  a  practical 
school  of  music,  with  a  dash  of  '  kinaesthesis,'  cenesthesis,  and  tactile  sen- 
sations of  the  tympanum  to  give  it  relish.  A  law  of  diffusion  of  stimulus 
in  the  brain  ascribed  to  Alexander  Bain  of  blessed  memory — whose  ghost 
still  walks  some  ancient  galleries  of  thought  in  France — gives  us  dynamo- 
geny  ;  and  pleasure  is  dynamogeny.  Fe"re  is  called  upon  to  establish  that 
rising  pitch  gives  more,  and  falling  pitch  less  of  this  dynamogeny.  Such 
motor  elements  we  learn  are  all  that  the  composer  can  put  into  music — no 
pictures  or  ideas  or  the  like.  Even  the  semi-circular  canals  are  not  for- 
gotten as  a  modest  idea  to  explain  the  puzzling  trinity  of  parts  in  common 
chords.  Every  harmonic  in  a  tone  is  supposed  to  have  its  own  series  of 
harmonics  again  :  the  authors  have  even  reckoned  out  these  harmonics  of 
harmonics  and  have  totalled  them  to  15  dos,  12  sols,  10  mis,  etc.  Things 
are  bad  enough  as  it  is,  but  this  welter  of  sounds  outbabels  Babel. 


238  NEW  BOOKS. 

The  musical  analysis  and  discussion  of  the  more  complex  problems  are 
often  good  on  the  '  psychological '  side  and  always  stimulating  to  reflexion, 
even  if  only  as  a  counter-irritant.  As  an  instance  the  problem  of  the  dif- 
ference between  major  and  minor  keys  may  be  mentioned.  But  the  theory 
of  resolution,  by  which  every  note  is  held  to  move  to  its  successor  by  step 
of  a  fourth  or  fifth  is  absurd  ;  for  it  requires  the  voices  to  cross  in  the 
most  hopelessly  irregular  way.  It  is  equally  absurd  to  suggest  that  every 
dissonance  is  reducible  to  one  or  more  '  rectified '  tritones — the  tritone 
b-f,  for  example,  is  supposed  to  resolve  by  b  moving  to  e'  and  f  to  c'. 
Surely  the  *  conventional '  diatonic  leading  of  the  voices  is  not  merely  an 
external  appearance  that  is  saved  from  being  purely  illusory  merely  be- 
cause it  is  helpful  to  vocal  execution.  In  this  fundamental  type  of  error, 
however,  the  authors  by  no  means  stand  alone. 

Writers  on  music  only  too  frequently  blind  themselves  to  basal  facts  by 
ascribing  them  to  the  difficulties  of  vocal  execution,  rejoicing  the  while  in 
the  fact  that  these  difficulties  no  longer  tyrannise  over  musical  composition. 
Nowadays  every  note  can  be  played  with  equal  ease  on  many  instruments. 
They  forget  to  notice  that  the  voice  has  no  greater  difficulty  in  singing 
any  one  note  than  another.  The  difficulty  for  all  instruments  is  to  play 
or  rather  to  use  musically  some  notes  after  certain  other  notes.  This 
musical  difficulty — quite  apart  from  any  physical  difficulty,  say  of  a  great 
leap,  that  may  exist — is  largely  a  matter  of  ear  ;  and  the  ear's  difficulty  is 
the  difficulty  the  mind  feels  in  passing  from  certain  notes  to  some  others. 
And  the  difficulty  of  that  mind-passage  is  there  whether  you  listen  to  an 
electric  pianola  or  to  your  own  voice.  It  helps  to  form  the  aesthetic  value 
of  the  work. 

The  second  larger  half  of  the  book,  characterising  the  great  masters  of 
music,  is  full  of  interest,  and — with  various  omissions — would  in  itself 
make  a  stimulating  volume  of  musical  analysis. 

HENRY  J.  WATT. 

A  Critical  History  of  Greek   Philosophy.     By  W.  T.    STAGE.      London  : 
Macmillan  &  Co,  1920.     Pp.  xiv,  386. 

When  one  has  said  that  Mr.  Stace's  work  is  well-meant,  one  has  said  about 
all  that  there  is  to  say  for  it.  The  execution  certainly  does  not  warrant 
the  description  of  the  book  on  the  title-page  as  a  "  critical "  history. 
The  author's  method  is  to  boil  down  Zeller,  introducing  from  time  to  time, 
in  the  earlier  chapters,  a  few  modifications  from  Burnet's  Early  Greek 
Philosophy.  The  part  of  the  book  for  which  Early  Greek  Philosophy  is 
not  available  is  mainly  pure  Zeller.  Mr.  Stace  regards  himself  as  thus,  in 
the  main,  reproducing  what  he  frequently  calls  "  the  traditional  "  view. 
Unfortunately  on  some  very  important  matters,  such  as  the  real  signifi- 
cance of  the  figure  of  Socrates,  and  on  a  good  many  matters  of  secondary 
moment,  his  "traditional"  view  does  not  mean  that  which  has  the  sup- 
port of  continuous  ancient  tradition  going  back  to  men  who  were  in  a  posi- 
tion to  know  the  historical  facts,  but  merely  the  view  which  deference  to 
the  authority  of  Zeller  made  customary  in  the  nineteenth  century,  a  very 
different  thing.  A  more  serious  defect  is  that  Mr.  Stace  never  thinks  it 
necessary  to  tell  his  readers  what  available  sources  of  evidence  there  are 
for  the  various  parts  of  his  narrative,  and  only  rarely  indicates  the  grounds 
on  which  he  arrives  at  his  own  conclusions  about  .debatable  questions. 
The  accounts  of  the  Sceptics  and  Neo-Platonists  are  so  very  misleading  that 
one  suspects  the  author  in  this  part  of  his  work  at  any  rate  to  be  epitomis- 
ing and  sitting  in  judgment  on  what  he  has  never  read. 

A.  E.  TAYLOR. 


NEW  BOOKS.  239 

La  Vita  dello  Spirito.  By  ARMANDO  CARLINI.  Florence  :  Vallecchi, 
1921.  Pp.  225. 

L'Azione.  By  MAURICE  BLONDEL,  translated  into  Italian  by  ERNESTO 
CODIGNOLA.  Florence:  Vallecchi,  1920.  Vol.  i.,  pp.  284;  Vol.  ii., 
pp.  371. 

Signer  Carlini's  book  had  its  origin  in  a  course  of  lectures,  delivered  at 
the  University  of  Pisa  in  1920-1921,  and  intended  to  expound  some  of  the 
concepts  of  present-day  idealism,  and  show  their  greater  concreteness  and 
more  realistic  character  as  compared  with  the  older  idealisms.  If  anyone 
wants  to  ba  introduced  straightway  into  the  motive,  aim  and  direction 
of  the  philosophical  movement, — perhaps  best  described  by  linking  together 
four  names,  Bergson — Blondel — Croce — Gentile,  he  will  find  no  better 
propaedeutic  than  this.  The  author,  whose  valuable  work  on  Locke  we 
noticed  recently,  gives  us  not  a  historical  or  biographical  account  of  present 
philosophers  and  their  theories,  but  a  lucid  exposition  of  the  leading  con- 
cept which  underlies  their  different  expressions — elan  vital,  action,  spirito, 
atto  puro — a  new  concept  of  history. 

The  importance  in  this  connexion  of  Blondel's  concept,  based  like  that 
of  Kant's  Practical  Reason  on  the  Moral  Law,  is  especially  emphasised  by 
Signer  Carlini.  To  most  of  us  Blondel  is  no  more  than  a  name.  His 
book  IS  Action,  recognised  when  it  appeared  in  1893  as  a  philosophical 
work  of  the  first  order,  a  second  edition  being  almost  immediately  called 
for,  unfortunately  aroused  such  violent  animosity  in  Catholic  circles  that 
the  author  withdrew  it,  and  so  effectually  that  copies  are  now  excessively 
rare.  (The  Bodleian  is  believed  to  be  the  only  public  library  to  possess 
one.)  Against  the  author's  wish,  though  not  we  understand  actually  in 
defiance  of  his  authority,  a  translation  of  it  is  included  in  the  new  series 
of  Philosophical  Manuals,  II  Pensiero  Moderno,  now  in  course  of  publication 
by  Messrs.  Vallecchi  of  Florence.  The  translator  Signor  Codignola  is  also 
the  general  editor  of  the  series.  He  says  in  a  note :  "I  have  been  in- 
duced to  undertake  this  translation  in  the  firm  hope  that  to-day  at  last, 
both  without  and  within  the  Catholic  church,  our  minds  are  better  dis- 
posed to  understand  one  of  the  most  powerful,  most  religious  and  most 
profoundly  human,  voices  in  the  whole  history  of  philosophy". 

H.  WILDON  CARR. 


Contribution  del  Lenguaje  a  la  Filosofia  de  los  Valores.  By  JUAN 
ZARAGUETA  BENGOECHEA,  with  a  Contestaci6n  by  E.  SANZ  Y  ESCARTIN, 
Count  of  Lizarraga.  Madrid  :  Jaime  Rates,  1920.  Pp.  221. 

The  idea  underlying  Senor  Zaragiieta  Bengoechea's  work  is  excellent  and 
worthy  of  all  applause.  There  is  much  light  to  be  thrown  on  philosophic 
problems  in  general,  and  on  the  problem  of  values  in  particular,  from  the 
study  of  language.  For  language  reveals  what  ideas  have  so  insistently 
forced  themselves  upon  human  attention  that  words  have  had  to  be  coined 
to  express  them.  It  attests  therefore  the  use  and  usefulness  of  an  idea. 
It  proves  also  that  common  thought  is  often  ages  in  advance  of  philosophic 
'  reflexion '.  For  example  European  .philosophy  did  not  discover  the 
problem  of  the  Self  before  Descartes  ;  but  European  languages  had  em- 
ployed personal  pronouns  from  the  first.  We  may  be  sure  then  that  a 
philosophic  problem  recognised  by  language  is  a  real  problem.  We  may 
take  it  also  that  though  language  is  plastic  and  to  be  moulded  by  those 
who  master  it,  which  is  the  reason  why  the  intellectual  development  of  a 
people  can  be  deduced  from  its  language,  its  initial  testimony  is  honest 


240  NEW  BOOKS. 

and  uncorrupted  by  sectarian  prejudice.  Decidedly  then  the  exploration 
of  language  should  be  one  of  the  first  steps  in  a  philosophic  inquiry.  But 
the  exploration  of  language  is  apt  to  be  sterile  and  even  misleading,  if  it  is 
confined  to  a  single  language  :  for  grammatical  idioms  are  then  easily 
mistaken  for  necessities  of  thought.  Languages  should  be  studied  com- 
paratively to  extract  their  thought-contact :  it  is  then  found  that  it  is 
precisely  the  differences  and  lacunae  in  the  various  languages,  taken  in 
conjunction  with  the  differences  in  the  thinkers  that  use  them,  that  are 
most  illuminating.  His  omission  to  compare  the  Spanish  vocabulary  of 
valuation  with  that  of  other  tongues  is  perhaps  one  reason  why  Senor 
Zaragiieta's  study  is  somewhat  disappointing  and  leads  to  no  very  definite 
conclusions.  He  has  also  cast  his  net  too  wide,  making  (somewhat  cursory) 
mention  of  all  terms  more  or  less  directly  connected  with  the  human  habit 
of  valuation.  He  would  probably  have  elicited  more  if  he  had  concentrated 
upon  the  primary  and  essential  values  and  studied  them  more  profoundly 
and  in  connexion  with  their  equivalents  in  other  languages.  For  the  rest 
his  attitude  is  that  of  a  Spanish  ecclesiastic,  competently  trained  in  the 
Louvain  School  of  Philosophy  under  Cardinal  Mercier,  and  the  occasion 
for  his  work  was  his  reception  into  the  Royal  Academy  of  Moral  and 
Political  Sciences. 

F.  C.  S.  SCHILLER. 

Erlebnis  und  Wissen,  Kritischer  Gang  durch  die  englische  Psychologic. 
By  HANS  RUIN.     Helsingfors  :  Soderstrom  &  Co.,  1921.     Pp.  303. 

This  work  consists  of  a  rapid,  not  to  say  cursory,  survey  of  English  psy- 
chology from  Bacon  and  Hobbes  to  Bain  and  Spencer,  with  a  chapter  of 
'  parallels,'  touching  (lightly)  on  Herbart,  Fechner,  Lotze,  Wundt,  Taine, 
Bergson,  and  James.  It  aims  at  showing  that  all  attempts  to  represent 
the  mind  as  passive  and  to  dispense  with  the  self  have  failed,  and  are 
bound  to  fail.  There  is  nothing  very  new  in  its  criticism  of  associationism, 
and  it  also  draws  the  conventional  inference  (apparently  under  the  inspira- 
tion of  Husserl)  that  epistemological  criticism  is  the  presupposition  of 
psychology,  and  the  only  possible  alternative  to  associationism.  The 
author,  however,  diverges  from  the  conventional  apriorism  by  combining 
this  conclusion  with  a  preference  for  the  Erlebnis  of  immediate  experience 
over  reflective  thought,  and  endeavours  (faintly)  to  attribute  a  similar  pre- 
ference to  Kant.  It  has  evidently  not  occurred  to  him  in  the  first  place 
that  the  antithesis  of  associationism  and  apriorism  breaks  down  in  so  far  as 
Hume's  psychology  was  a  presupposition  of  Kant's  problem,  and,  secondly, 
that  there  is  no  valid  inference  from  the  falsity  of  associationism  to  the 
truth  of  apriorism,  because  an  alternative  to  both  is  thinkable  and  tenable. 
For  since  both  are  (predominantly)  intellectualistic,  their  joint  fashion  of 
describing  psychic  processes  has  merely  to  be  given  up,  to  render  it  perfectly 
possible  to  account  in  psychology  for  all  the  puzzles  that  were  supposed  to 
demand  a  /iera/3ao-iff  eis  aXXo  yevos,  and  a  recourse  to  apriorist  epistem- 
ology.  In  other  words,  an  activistic,  voluntaristic,  psychology  is  possible, 
which  is  much  more  radically  and  faithfully  empirical  than  the  old 
1  empiricism,'  and  free  from  its  logical  difficulties.  Indeed  this  line  of 
thought  would  probably  be  much  more  congenial  with  the  author's  aim  and 
temperament  than  the  merely  negative  attitude  of  apriorism,  which  regards 
as  spiritually  valuable  whatever  it  cannot  understand  :  but  he  evidently 
knows  very  little  about  modern  pragmatism.  He  just  alludes  to  it,  includes 
a  few  of  James's  books  in  his  bibliography,  and  criticises  his  account  of  the 
self  ;  but  he  has  evidently  overlooked  the  epistemological  bearing  of  the 
famous  last  chapter  in  the  Principles  of  Psychology  and  the  psychological 
importance  of  starting  from  a  psychic  continuum  instead  of  a  heap  of 


NEW  BOOKS.  241 

'  sensations  '.  Finally  it  may  be  noted  that  the  work,  though  appearing  in 
German,  is  evidently  a  translation  (presumably  from  the  Swedish),  effected 
with  the  aid  of  the  dictionary.  This  sometimes  leads  to  curiosities,  as  on 
page  104,  where  the  thought  to  be  conveyed  is  that  '  Reid  arbitrarily  cut 
down  the  sphere  of  consciousness  ' ;  unfortunately  the  word  used  does  not 
mean  '  circumscribe '. 

F.  C.  S.  SCHILLER. 


Received  also  : — 

H.  A.  Reyburn,  The  Ethical  Theory  of  Hegel,  Oxford,  Clarendon  Press, 

1921,  pp.  xx,  271. 

G.  Boas,  An  Analysis  of  Certain  Theories  of  Truth  (University  of  Cali- 
fornia Publications  in  Philosophy,  Vol.  II.,  No.  6),  Berkeley,  Uni- 
versity of  California  Press,  1921,  pp.  104. 
Sir  H.  Jones,  A  Faith  that  Enquires,  The  Gifford  Lectures  delivered  in 

the  University  of  Glasgow  in  the  years  1920  and  1921,  London, 

Macmillan  &  Co.,  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  x,  361. 
R.  W.  Sellars,  Evolutionary  Naturalism,  Chicago,  Open  Court  Publishing 

Co.,  1922,  pp.  xiii,  343. 
W.  E.  Johnson,  Logic  :  Part  II.,  Demonstrative  Inference,  Deductive  and 

Inductive,  Cambridge  University  Press,  1922,  pp.  xx,  258. 
G.  F.  Stout,  The  Nature  of  Universals  and  Propositions  (British  Academy, 

Annual  Philosophical  Lecture,   Henriette  Hertz  Trust),  London, 

H.  Milford,  pp.  18. 
Jahrbuch  fiir  Philosophic  und  phanomenologische  Forschung,  edited  by  E. 

Husserl,  Vol.  V.,  Halle  a.  d.  S.,  M.  Niemeyer,  1922,  pp.  ix,  628. 
Sir  H.  Jones  and  J.  H.  Muirhead,   The  Life  and  Philosophy  of  Edward 

Caird,  Glasgow,  Maclehose,  Jackson  &  Co.,  1921,  pp.  xi,  381. 
B.  Petronievics,  L'Evolution  Universelle,  Paris,  F.  Alcan,  1921,  pp.  viii, 

212. 

M.  Billia,  Bisurrezione,  Rome,  Rassegna  Nazionale,  1921,  pp.  9. 
P.     Feldkeller,     Graf   Keyserlings    Erkenntnisweg   zum    Ubersinnlichen, 

Darmstadt,  O.  Reichl,  1922,  pp.  191. 
G.  Gentile,  The  Theory  of  Mind  as  Pure  Act,  trans,  by  H.  Wildon  Carr, 

London,  Macmillan  &  Co.,  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  xxvii,  280. 
J.  M.  Baldwin,  Le  Mtfdiat  et  L'Immediat,  trans,  by  E.  Philippi  (Biblio- 

theque  de  Philosophic  Contemporaine),  Paris,  F.  Alcan,  1921,  pp. 

xii,  324. 
L.  Laberthonniere,  II  Realismo  Cristiano  e  L'Idealismo  Greco,  trans,  by 

P.  Gobetti,  Florence,  VaUecchi,  1922,  pp.  180. 
H.  Weyl,  Space,  Time,  Matter,  trans,  by  H.  L.  Brose,  London,  Methuen 

&  Co.  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  xi,  330. 
A.  Aliotta,  La  Teoria  di  Einstein  e  le  Mutevoli  Prospettive  del  Mondo, 

Palermo,  R.  Sandron,  1922,  pp.  120. 
E.  Picard,  La  Theorie  de  la  Relativite'  et  ses  Applications  a  I' Astronomic, 

Paris,  Gauthier-Villars  et  Cie,  1922,  pp.  27. 
E.  M.  Lemeray,  L'fither  Actual  et  ses  Pre'curseurs  (Simple  Recit),  Paris, 

Gauthier-Villars  et  Cie,  1922,  pp.  ix,  141. 
E.  Goblot,  Le  Systeme  des  Sciences,  Le  Vrai,  V Intelligible,  et  le  Re'el,  Paris, 

A.  Colin,  1922,  pp.  259. 
E.  H.  Neville,  Multilinear  Functions  of  Direction,  Cambridge  University 

Press,  1921,  pp.  79. 
W.  H.  R.  Rivers,  Instinct  and  the  Unconscious,  2nd  Edition,  Cambridge 

University  Press,  1922,  pp.  viii,  277. 

16 


242  NEW  BOOKS. 

J.    Pikler,    Theorie   der   Empfindungsqualitdt    als    Abbildes    des   Reizes 

(Schriften  zur  Anpassungstheorie  des  Empfindungsvorganges,  Heft 

4),  Leipzig,  J.  A.  Barth,  1922,  pp.  107. 
Handbuch  psychologischer   Hilfsmittel    der  psychiatrischen  Diagnostik, 

edited  by  O.  Lipmann,  Leipzig,  J.  A.  Barth,  1922,  pp.  x,  297. 
O.  Jespersen,  Language :  Its  Nature,  Development  and  Origin,  London, 

G.  Allen  &  Unwin,  Ltd.,  pp.  448. 
G.  E.  Shuttle-worth  and  W.  A.  Potts,  Mentally  Deficient  Children,  Their 

Treatment  and  Training,  5th  Edition,  London,  H.  K.  Lewis  &  Co., 

Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  xviii,  317. 
A.  Wyatt  Tilby,  The  Evolution  of  Consciousness,  London,   T.   Fisher 

Unwin,  pp.  256. 
F.  Heinemann,  Plotin,  Leipzig,  F.  Meiner,  1921,  pp.  xiii,  318. 

E.  Gilson,  Etudes  de  Philosophie  Medievale  (Publications  de  la  Faculte" 

des  Lettres  de  1'Universite'  de  Strasbourg,  Fasc.  3),    Strasbourg, 

Palais  de  1'Universite',  1921,  pp.  vii,  291. 
A.  Levi,  La  Filosofia  di  Giorgio  Berkeley  (Metafisica  e  Gnoseologia),  Turin, 

Fratelli  Bocca,  1922,  pp.  103. 
X.  Leon,  Fichte  et  Son  Temps,  Vol.  I.  (1762-1799),  Paris,  A.  Colin,  1922, 

pp.  xvi,  649. 

F.  Fiorentino,   Compendio  di  Storia  della  Filosofia,  Vol.  II.,   Part  I., 

Lafilosofia  moderna,  Florence,  Vallecchi,  1922,  pp.  358. 
C.  K.   Ogden,   I.  A.  Richards  and  James   Wood,   The   Foundations   of 
Esthetics,  London,  G.  Allen  &  Unwin,  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  92. 

G.  H.  Jaques,  A  System  of  ^Esthetics,  Vol.  I.,  Dublin,  1921,  pp.  165. 

R.   Eucken,  The  Spiritual  Outlook  of  Europe,  London,  The  Faith  Press, 

1922,  pp.  96. 
R.  J.  Fox,  The  Finding  of  Shiloh  or  The  Mystery  of  God  "Finished," 

London,  C.  Palmer,  pp.  xv,  371. 


VII— PHILOSOPHICAL  PEEIODICALS. 

BRITISH  JOURNAL  OF  PSYCHOLOGY.  Vol.  xi.,  Part  2.  January,  1921 
Henry  Head,  in  a  paper  on  "  Disorders  of  Symbolic  Thinking  and  Ex- 
pression," records  observations  on  patients  suffering  from  brain  lesions. 
These  observations  and  tests  led  him  to  conclude  that  a  unilateral  lesion 
of  the  brain,  affecting  the  use  of  language,  disturbs  a  number  of  psychical 
processes,  which  cannot  be  grouped  under  such  headings  as  "speech," 
"  reading,"  "  writing,"  "  motor,"  or  "  sensory  "  activities,  or  any  other  a 
priori  categories.  He  applies  to  them  the  term  "symbolic  thinking  and 
expression,"  because  they  consist  mainly  of  the  use  of  symbols  in  language 
and  in  thought  :  but  it  is  symbols  used  in  a  particular  manner  which  are 
affected,  and  not  all  symbolic  representations.  Yet  the  term  is  not  a  de- 
finition, for  this  group  of  functions  cannot  be  comprised  within  any  single 
general  conception.  The  various  manifestations  of  aphasia  and  allied  dis- 
orders of  speech  cannot  be  explained  by  destruction  of  sensory  images. 
These  may  remain  intact,  although  they  cannot  be  used  voluntarily  as 
part  of  the  symbolic  mechanism  of  language.  Finally  Dr.  Head  concludes 
that  his  researches  show  that  the  two  aspects  of  meaning  involved  in  the 
use  of  symbols  may  be  separated  by  suitable  lesions  of  the  brain.  C. 
Lloyd  Morgan  contributes  an  article  on  "Psychical  Selection  :  Expres- 
sion and  Impression  ".  He  discusses  especially  the  psychology  of  sexual 
attraction  of  birds,  regarding  the  display  of  the  male  as  instinctive  in  part 
at  least,  there  not  being  necessarily  any  intention  to  produce  an  effect ;  the 
"  selection  "  by  the  female  is  regarded  not  as  a  type  of  choice,  but  as  an 
inevitable  response  to  the  more  powerful  stimulus.  Expression  is  a  sub- 
species of  behaviour  differentiated  from  other  modes  of  behaviour  in  that  its 
utility  lies  in  the  impression  it  produces  on  some  other  organism  ;  while 
the  impression  is  a  sub-species  of  presentation  differing  from  other  presen- 
tations in  that  what  is  presented  is  expressive  behaviour  on  the  part  of 
some  other  organism.  That  the  same  expression  in  the  behaviour  of 
animals  seems  to  us  to  produce  in  different  situations  very  different  be- 
haviour on  the  part  of  the  recipient  of  the  behaviour  impressions,  is  pro- 
bably due  to  the  fact  that  we  consider  these  expressions  in  isolation  from 
their  context,  the  animal  in  reality  being  ' '  responsive  rather  to  the  total 
presented  situation  than  to  details  ".  In  the  "  Nature  of  Verse  "  E.  W. 
Scripture  describes  an  experiment  which  he  undertook  to  settle  a  dispute 
between  two  professors  of  Greek  at  Harvard  and  Yale  as  to  the  nature  of 
English  verse,  the  former  saying  that  it  consisted  of  long  and  short  syl- 
lables, the 'latter  that  it  was  composed  of  loud  and  weak  syllables.  By 
appropriate  apparatus  for  recording  vibrations  due  to  speech  Scripture 
obtained  records  from  which  he  concludes  that  the  rhythm  of  verse  depends 
on  loudness  (or  softness),  length  of  syllable,  and  clearness  of  enunciation 
and  pitch,  the  stressed  syllables  being  better  enunciated  and  of  higher 
pitch  W.  Whately  Smith  in  his  "  Experiments  on  Memory  and  Atfec- 
tive  Tone  "  estimated  the  affective  value  of  words  by  the  psycho-galvanic 
reflex,  the  reaction  time,  and  by  Jung's  reproduction  test,  the  first  proving 
"  by  far  the  most  delicate  test  of  affective  tone  ".  He  concluded  (1)  that 


244  PHILOSOPHICAL   PEEIODICALS. 

so  far  as  the  affective  tone  detected  by  the  psycho-galvanic  reflex  is  con- 
cerned, its  influence  may  be  exerted  in  two  diametrically  opposite  direc- 
tions ;  the  fact  that  a  given  word  evokes  well-marked  affective  tone  may 
lead  to  its  being  better  remembered  than  a  less  intensely  toned  word,  or 
may  lead  to  its  being  forgotten  more  quickly.  (2)  The  kind  of  affective 
tone  which  is  shown  by  Jung's  reproduction  test  tends  to  impede  the  re- 
membering of  the  words  concerned.  Affective  tone  which  helps  remem- 
brances he  calls  "  positive,"  that  which  hinders  remembrance  he  calls 
"  negative  "  tone.  The  author  explicitly  leaves  on  one  side  the  relation  of 
positive  and  negative  tone  to  pleasant  and  unpleasant  tones.  Other 
articles  are  as  follows:  Frank  Watts,  ''The  Outlook  for  Vocational 
Psychology";  Godfrey  H.  Thomson,  "Report  on  the  Selection  of 
Children  for  Higher  Education  at  Hamburg"  ;  Carveth  Read,  "Critical 
Notice  of  A.  F.  Shand's  'The  Foundations  of  Character'".  Part  3. 
April,  1921.  In  an  article  on  "Infantile  Psyche,  with  special  reference 
to  Visual  Projection/'  David  Forsyth  discusses  the  vivid  visualisation  of 
young  children,  amounting  as  it  does  at  times  to  hallucination.  He  sug- 
gests that  "  a  mere  infant  is  unable  to  appreciate  the  essential  difference 
between  objects  which  are  seen  in  the  outer  world  and  those  which  are  the 
product  of  its  own  mechanism  ".  The  reality  of  these  latter  is  emphasised 
by  the  reality  of  the  emotions  which  give  rise  to  them.  Night  fears  are 
not  due  to  hallucinations,  but  awakening  fear  rouses  memories  associated 
with  fear  and  these  memories  are  then  projected  as  hallucinations,  which 
aie  regarded  as  the  cause  of  the  fear.  (In  a  later  paragraph,  however,  the 
writer  attributes  fear  of  the  dark  to  visual  hallucinations.)  The  paper 
discusses  also  the  relation  of  these  characteristics  of  infantile  mind  to 
Freud's  pleasure  and  reality  principles,  to  magic  and  the  belief  in  spirits 
and  demons,  and  also  deals  with  rationalisation  in  connexion  with  magic. 
F.  C.  Bartlett  contributes  an  article  on  "The  Functions  of  Images". 
The  function  of  images  was  studied  in  the  recall  of  pictures,  and  in  the 
association  of  signs  with  words.  It  was  found  that  images  reinstated 
mainly  by  the  aid  of  affective  cues  were  vague  and  unanalysed,  the  function 
of  affection  in  reproduction  being  "  to  reinstate  a  situation  rather  than  a 
specific  object  ".  The  occurrence  of  definite  visual  imagery  tended  to  set 
up  an  attitude  of  confidence  in  the  accuracy  of  the  reproductions,  both  of 
pictures  and  of  signs,  though  this  confidence  was  often  unjustified.  Re- 
liance on  visual  imagery  resulted  especially  in  the  forgetting  of  order  of 
succession  ;  those  who  relied  on  vocalisation  of  words  were  very  accurate 
in  their  memory  of  order.  It  is  suggested  that  the  primitive  sensory 
image  is  vague  and  schematic — contrary  to  the  supposition  that  it  is  definite 
a  ad  becomes  vague  and  general  through  the  repetition  of  varying  impres- 
sions. One  function  of  the  image  seemed  to  be  to  reinforce  the  tendency 
to  prompt  response  ;  its  close  connexion  with  emotion  helped  to  supply 
confidence,  the  substitution  of  words  leading  away  from  the  "  reinstate- 
ment of  material  in  close  relation  to  emotions  ".  The  other  articles  in  the 
number  are  as  follows  :  H.  Hartridge,  "  A  Vindication  of  the  Resonance 
Hypothesis  of  Audition"  ;  J.  C.  Fliigel,  "  A  Minor  Study  of  Nyctopsis  "  ; 
LI.  Wynn  Jones,  "A  Method  of  Measuring  Nyctopsis,  with  some  Re- 
sults ;  "  S.  M.  Haggard,  "  A  Case  of  Somnambulism  "  ;  F.  C.  Bartlett, 
"  Critical  Notice  of  C.  Read's  '  The  Origin  of  Man  and  of  his  Supersti- 
tions '"  ;  F.  C.  Bartlett,  "  Critical  Notice  of  W.  McDougall's  '  The  Group 
Mind '"  ;  T.  H.  Pear,  "  Critical  Notice  of  W.  H.  R.  Rivers's  '  Instinct 
and  the  Unconscious  '  ". 

JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY,  xviii.  (1921),  11.  M.  T.  McCIure.  '  "  Crises  " 
in  the  Life  of  Reason.'  [Traces  "  the  natural  history  of  reason  "  in  the  phil- 
osophy of  Santayana.]  M.  Picard.  '  The  Co-ordinate  Character  of  Feeling 


PHILOSOPHICAL   PERIODICALS.  245 

and  Cognition. '  [Concludes  that "  the  case  for  feeling  as  a  co-ordinate  aspect 
of  conscious  activity  rests  partly  on  the  universal  presence  of  one  or  both  of 
the  affective  qualities  in  all  conscious  states,  partly  on  a  certain  independence 
of  cognition  manifested  by  feeling  in  the  production  of  moods".]  F.  R. 
Bichowsky.  '  The  Basic  Assumption  of  Experimental  Science.'  [Is  merely 
that  the  data  of  science  "be  organised  into  a  logical  system  the  laws  of 
which  can  be  tested  ".]  xviii.,  12.  W.  H.  Sheldon.  '  Prof.  Dewey,  the  Pro- 
tagonist of  Democracy.'  [Reviews  Dewey 's  '  Reconstruction  in  Philosophy,' 
declaring  that  "  his  programme  is  a  revolt  against  superiority,"  and  defend- 
ing "  the  spectator  view  of  knowledge  "  by  urging  that  the  great  philosophers 
"  wrote  on  ethics  and  politics  and  tried  to  influence  the  society  of  their  day  ". 
Prof.  Sheldon's  attitude  explains  perhaps  why  Prof.  Dewey  finds  Peking  a 
healthier  place  than  New  York  ;  but  neither  party  to  the  dispute  seems  to 
question  the  assumption  that  the  American  system  is  what  it  is  called.] 
J.  J.  Toohey.  'The  Distribution  of  the  Predicate.'  [The  traditional 
doctrine  is  confuted  by  the  validity  of  the  partial  inverse  of  an  A  proposi- 
tion.] Q.  Boas.  '  A  Source  of  the  Plotinian  Mysticism.'  [Besides  its 
empirical  root  in  the  mystic  vision  it  has  another  in  the  principle  that  only 
the  like  knows  the  like.  Hence,  to  know,  the  mind  must  intuitively  ap- 
prehend its  object.]  xviii. ,  13.  F.  J.  E.  Woodbridge.  '  Mind  Discerned.' 
[Concerning  the  relations  of  "  mind  in  the  transcendental  sense,  the  sum 
total  and  mere  fact  of  existence,"  and  "the  mind  which  is  studied  in 
psychology  ".  The  former  is  a  '  type  of  structure  '.]  M.  Picard.  '  The 
Unity  of  Consciousness. '  [Argues  that  C.  A.  Strong's  '  Origin  of  Conscious- 
ness,' has  shown  that "  there  is  no  such  unity  ".]  xviii.,  14.  [Not  received.] 
R.  B.  Perry.  'The  Cognitive  Interest  and  its  Refinements.'  K.  S. 
Quthrie.  '  Rejoinder  to  Mr.  Boas'  attack  on  Guthrie's  Plotinus.'  xviii., 
15.  S.  L.  Pressey.  '  Empiricism  versus  Formalism  in  Work  with  Mental 
Tests.'  [Replies  to  Ruml  in  xviii.  7  and  deprecates  excess  of  statistical 
elaboration.]  A.  J.  Snow.  'A  Note  on  the  Role  of  Mathematics  in 
Physics.'  [It  is  "not  that  of  a  discipline  independent  of  facts,  and 
mathematics  does  not  give  us  truth  a  priori  ".]  xviii.  16.  J.  M.  Fletcher. 
'  Geneticism  as  a  Heuristic  Principle  in  Psychology.'  [Geneticism  is 
historicism  in  psychology,  and  easily  leads  to  a  confusion  of  history  and 
valuation.  It  is  open  to  six  objections  :  (1)  Continuity  and  the  non-occur- 
rence of  novelty  is  a  rationalistic  logical  postulate  ;  (2)  The  tracing  of  past 
history  is  always  arbitrarily  arrested  at  some  point  ;  (3)  History  is  not  the 
sole  determinant  of  value  ;  (4)  Historical  continuity  is  compatible  with 
radical  change  in  function  and  meaning  ;  (5)  Like  '  analyticism, '  geneticism 
falsely  assumes  that  it  can  get  back  to  a  'simple'  ;  (6)  Whether  or  no 
science  is  bound  to  ignore  values,  it  must  not  confuse  values  and  facts.  ] 
E.  L.  Schaub.  The  Annual  Meeting  of  the  Western  Division  of  the 
American  Philosophical  Association.  D.  Drake.  '  Philosophy  as  Work  and 
Play.'  [Philosophic  problems  are  divisible  into  those  which  "  have  appreci- 
able practical  bearings  "  and  "  those  whose  solution  would  make  no  or  slight 
difference  to  practice  ".  The  latter  are  'play'  and  include  metaphysics, 
God,  freedom  and  immortality  ;  they  are  justifiable  amusements,  though 
it  might  be  well  if  philosophers  would  devote  a  little  more  attention  to  the 
rational  ordering  of  human  life.]  xviii.  17.  W.  E.  Ritter.  '  The  Need 
of  a  New  English  Word  to  Express  Relation  in  Living  Nature, '  I.  [Seeing 
that  "the  Latin  gradior  upon  which  '  integration '  is  founded  "  (sic  /)  is  un- 
satisfactory as  the  correlative  of  *  differentiation/  '  conferentiation '  is 
suggested.]  T.  L.  Kelly  and  L.  M.  Terman.  'Dr.  Ruml's  Criticism  of 
Mental  Test  Methods.'  [Cf.  xvii.,3.  Pleads  that  the  assumptions  attacked 
are  but  the  working  hypotheses  of  an  infant  science.]  xviii.  18.  H.  B. 
Smith.  'A  Spirit  which  Includes  the  Community.'  [Protests,  against 
Sabin  in  xvii.,  26,  that  "  wherever  there  exists  a  conflict  between  points  of 


246  PHILOSOPHICAL  PEEIODICALS. 

view,  there  there  is  a  mind".]  W.  E.  Ritter.  <  The  Need  of  a  New 
English  Word  to  Express  Relation  in  Living  Nature,'  II.  [Illustrates 
the  need  from  the  neuromusc.ular  system,  sex,  love,  and  the  American 
Constitution.]  xviii.,  19.  C.  I.  Lewis.  '  The  Structure  of  Logic  and  its 
Relation  to  other  Systems.'  [Classifies  logics  as:  (1)  the  'traditional/ 
which  claims  to  be  both  formal  and  "  concerned  with  the  actual  modes  of 
right  thinking  "  ;  (2)  the  l  modern  '  which  repudiates  formalism,  just  because 
it  concerns  itself  with  "the  actual  processes  of  right  thinking"  ;  (3)  the 
'new,'  which,  to  be  formal,  "renounces  all  attempts  to  portray"  the 
actual  discovery  of  truth.  The  third  does  not  regard  deduction  as  a  method 
of  proving  truth  and  regards  as  nugatory  attempts  to  establish  incontro- 
vertible truth  by  deductive  procedures.  For  it  '  logically  prior '  only 
means  '  deductively  more  powerful '  or  '  simpler  '.  The  necessity  of  '  pre- 
suppositions '  is  often  shown  to  mean  only  lack  of  imagination  or  ingenuity. 
The  possibility  of  a  plurality  of  beginnings  for  a  system  and  of  a  plurality 
of  equally  cogent  systems  is  recognised.  All  this  holds  of  the  fundamental 
laws  of  logic  also.  They  too  cannot  be  proved,  for  all  their  '  proofs  '  turn 
out  to  be  circular.  "  That  the  denial  of  a  proposition  leads  to  its  reafnr- 
mation,  by  no  means  establishes  its  truth."  This  is  true  also  of  false 
propositions.  A  bad  logic  can  be  constructed,  "  in  which  reasoning  badly 
according  to  bad  principles  we  get  consistently  bad  results  ".  "A  good 
logic  must  be  circular  "  ;  but  so  is  "  all  logic  and  pseudo-logic  ".  Illustra- 
tions follow,  e.g.,  it  is  not  self  contradictory  that '  there  are  no  propositions,' 
and  the  ambiguities  of  '  presuppose  '  are  exposed.  In  short  "  no  deductive 
system,  logic  itself  included,  can  justly  claim  to  be  demonstration  of 
certain  truth  from  indispensable  first  principles,"  and  the  claim  of  "the 
traditional  a  priori  "  is  baseless.]  D.  W.  Prall.  *  The  Aesthetic  Heresy.' 
['  *  The  only  source  of  value  is  a  mind  satisfied  with  a  particular  object  in 
its  contemplation,  and  the  only  test  of  value  is  such  satisfaction.  All 
value  is  thus  essentially  aesthetic."]  xviii.  20.  H.  M.  Kallen.  '  America 
and  the  Life  of  Reason.'  [A  brilliant  paper  on  Santayana's  Character 
and  Opinion  in  the  United  States.]  E.  B.  Holt.  '  On  the  Locus  of  Tele- 
ology :  A  Rejoinder.'  [To  L.  J.  Henderson,  cf.  xvii.,  16  and  14.]  xviii., 
21.  C.  E.  Ayres.  '  Instinct  and  Capacity  :  I.  The  Instinct  of  Belief-in- 
Instincts.'  [Makes  fun  of  the  sociologists  who  attribute  all  social  pheno- 
mena to  instincts  instead  of  to  institutions.]  A.  P.  Brogan.  'A 
Dilemma  about  Dilemmas.'  [Replies  to  T.  de  Laguna's  criticism  of  the 
Complex  Dilemma  in  xviii.,  9  by  showing  that  it  holds  only  if  '  or '  is 
taken  in  the  exclusive  sense  and  that  the  best  formal  logicians,  including 
those  mentioned  by  de  Laguna,  had  expressly  stipulated  for  a  non-exclusive, 
sense  of  'or'.]  H.  M.  Kallen.  '  America  and  the  Life  of  Reason,  II. 
[Deals  more  specifically  with  Santayana's  treatment  of  James  and  Royce, 
and  hints  that  he  was  temperamentally  unfit  to  understand  either  of 
them.]  xviii.,  22.  W.  H.  Sheldon.  'Is  the  Conservation  of  Energy 


Proved  of  the  Human  Body  ? '     [Shows  that  in  all  the  experiments  which 


that  all  "  human  behaviour  is  the  behaviour  of  institutions,"  and  "  civil- 
isation is  the  determination  of  behaviour  by  prescription  and  taboo  ".] 
J.  C.  Gregory.  '  The  Group  Spirit  and  the  Fear  of  the  Dead.'  ["  Primi- 
tive fear  of  the  dead  had  probably  a  complex  origin,  but  .  .  .  one  of 
its  motives  was  expulsion  from  the  group  by  the  dread  event  of  death 
...  he  who  was,  when  alive,  a  comrade  of  the  group,  might,  when  dead 
and  expelled,  be  intensely  feared  and  bitterly  hated."  Why  ?]  xviii.,  23. 
R.  C.  Qivler.  'The  Intellectual  Significance  of  the  Grasping  Reflex.' 
[An  ultra-behaviourist  attempt  to  trace  mental  development  from  the 


PHILOSOPHICAL   PERIODICALS.  247 

infant's  power  to  cling  to  a  stick  like  a  monkey  which  concludes  that  "the 
weight  of  the  evidence  is  overwhelmingly  in  favour  of  interpreting  the 
thought  process  as  ...  a  neuro-muscular  process,  and  not  a  cerebral 
mystery".]  T.  L.  Davis.  '  The  Sanity  of  Hamlet.'  ["He  was  aware  of 
the  essential  principles  of  logic  and  used  them  consciously.  He  used  them 
excessively  :  that  was  his  madness."]  xviii.,  24.  Z.  Z.  Kuo.  '  Giving 
up  Instincts  in  Psychology.'  [Attacks  instincts  on  behaviourist  principles 
as  no  better  than  *  innate  ideas  '  and  substitutes  for  them  an  endowment 
with  "a  great  number  of  units  of  reaction".]  J.  Dewey.  'Classicism 
as  an  Evangel.'  [The  classic  spirit  was  naive  and  unconscious  in  its  ac- 
ceptance of  limitation  by  the  actual ;  no  possibility  of  remoulding  reality 
had  yet  presented  itself.  But  "  modern  class-conscious  classicism  "  is  "a 
reversed  romanticism"  and  is  "preoccupied  with  salvation".]  xviii.,  25. 
W.  A.  Brown.  'The  Future  of  Philosophy  as  a  University  Study.' 
[The  philosophy  professors  are  killing  philosophy  by  narrow  specialism  and 
neglecting  its  function  of  correlating  and  unifying  the  many  sources  of 
knowledge.  Moreover  "  the  interest  of  thinking  for  thinking's  sake,  of 
denning  and  redefining,  analysing  and  reanalysing,  controverting  and  re- 
controverting,  not  for  the  sake  of  getting  anything  in  particular  accom- 
plished by  this  elaborate  paraphernalia  but  for  the  sake  of  showing  that 
you  are  cleverer  than  the  other  fellow  at  the  game  you  are  both  playing 
...  is  not  capital  enough  on  which  to  run  the  business  of  philosophy  in 
a  modern  university  ".]  R.  M.  Eaton.  '  The  Value  of  Theories.'  ["  The 
chief  value  of  a  scientific  construction  is  that  it  explains  experience  by 
making  it  a  consequence  of  a  deductive  system.  Explanatory  value  is  suf- 
ficient to  a  theory  ;  truth,  in  the  sense  of  factual  truth,  is  not  established 
and  is  not  a  necessary  value.  Indeed  those  qualities  which  make  a  theory 
a  good  explanation,  generality  and  penetration  beneath  fact,  are  the  very 
qualities  which  stand  in  the  way  of  proving  its  truth.  .  .  .  Further  there 
is  no  extraordinary  type  of  logic  which  can  be  called  inductive  logic.  .  .  . 
The  inductive  and  deductive  methods  coalesce."  This  omits  the  need  for 
the  empirical  verification  of  theoretic  deductions.]  xviii.,  26.  Q.  Santa= 
yana.  '  On  My  Friendly  Critics.'  [Excellent  banter,  replete  with  epi- 
grams and  autobiographical  touches.  E.g.,  "  Now  that  for  some  years  my 
body  has  not  been  visible  in  the  places  it  used  to  haunt  (my  mind,  even 
then,  being  often  elsewhere)  my  friends  in  America  have  fallen  into  the 
habit  of  thinking  of  me  as  dead,  and  with  characteristic  haste  and  kind 
ness,  they  are  writing  obituary  notices,  as  it  were,  on  my  life  and  works  ".] 
M.  Picard.  'A  Discussion  of  Mind  Discerned.''  [Woodbridge's  article 
in  xviii.,  13.]  xix.,  1.  A.  O.  Lovejoy.  'Pragmatism  and  the  New 
Materialism.'  [Attacks  B.  H.  Bode's  attempt  to  combine  pragmatism  and 
behaviourism.  Cf.  xviii.,  1,  and  xvii.,  22,  23.]  L.  P.  Boggs.  '  A  Partial 
Analysis  of  Faith.'  [The  faith  attitude  "  suspends  all  efforts  and  waits  for 
an  inspiration  or  guiding  thought  to  come  ;  if  from  within,  we  call  it  auto- 
suggestion or  intuition ;  if  from  another,  it  is  called  suggestion  ;  if  it  ap- 
pears to  come  from  a  divine  source,  it  is  prayer  or  an  answer  to  prayer  ".] 
xix.,  2.  J.  Dewey.  'An  Analysis  of  Reflective  Thought.'  [Replies  to 
the  criticism  of  his  logic  by  L.  Buermeyer  in  xvii.,  25,  explaining  that 
"  induction  I  take  to  be  a  movement  from  facts  to  meaning  ;  deduction  a 
development  of  meanings,  an  exhibition  of  implications,  while  I  hold  that 
the  connexion  between  fact  and  meaning  is  made  only  by  an  act  in  the 
ordinary  physical  sense  of  the  word  act,  that  is,  by  experiment  involving 
movement  of  the  body  and  change  in  surrounding  conditions.  .  .  .  Facts, 
data,  are  logically  speaking  particulars,  while  meaning  functions  as  a  uni- 
versal." There  are  no  "  ready-made  or  given  particulars  and  universals, 
data  and  meanings  "  .  .  .  "  the  question  for  present  knowledge  is  whether 
the  old  case  or  rule  is  or  is  not  applicable  to  the  new  one.  Many  of  our 


248  PHILOSOPHICAL   PERIODICALS. 

common  errors  come  from  assuming  that  what  is  known  in  some  cases  is 
also  knowledge  for  the  case  in  hand."]  J.  R.  Kantor.  'The  Nervous 
System,  Psychological  Fact  or  Fiction  ? '  [Maintains  that  "  a  genuinely 
critical  search  will  reveal  not  a  single  valid  principle  of  explanation  which 
psychology  has  derived  from  physiology  ".] 

LOGOS.  RIVISTA  INTERNATIONALE  DI  FILOSOFIA.  Anno  iv.,  Fasc.  2. 
April-June,  1921.  J.  de  Menasce.  Essai  d'une  theorie  du  langage. 
[The  author's  thesis  is  based  on  the  view  of  Paulhan  that  man  is  a  non- 
social  being  forced  by  necessity  to  live  in  social  conditions.  Language  is 
not  merely  a  means  of  inter-communication  ;  it  is  also,  for  the  individual 
man,  a  means  of  "fixing"  his  thought.  Its  social  importance  is  not 
merely  that  it  enables  us  to  impart  and  receive  information,  but  that  it 
binds  the  utterer  to  his  pledge.  Hence  the  universal  moral  approval  of 
the  man  who  never  "  goes  back  on  his  word  ".  The  development  of 
language  may  take  place  in  either  of  two  directions.  The  effort  may  be 
made — necessarily  without  final  success — to  communicate  the  intimately 
personal  and  incommunicable,  and  thus  the  language  of  lyric  poetry  is 
created  :  or  the  function  of  "  fixing  "  thought  may  be  developed,  and  then 
we  get  the  language  of  science.  The  speech  of  the  ordinary  man  is  inter- 
mediate between  these  extremes,  but  as  might  be  expected  in  view  of  the 
moral  importance  of  being  able  to  "  count  on  a  man's  word,"  the  tendency 
towards  science  preponderates  over  that  to  wards  lyricism.]  L.  Limentani. 
Roberto  Ardigb.  [A  warm  eloge  pronounced  at  Palermo  March  19th, 
1921.]  A.  Aliotta.  L'idealismo  gnoseologico.  [Traces  the  development 
from  the  "empirical  idealism  "  of  Berkeley  through  the  "transcendental  " 
or  epistemological  idealism  of  Kant  and  the  attempts  of  Fichte,  Schelling, 
and  Hegel  to  "  transcend  "  Kant  to  the  "  absolute  idealism  "  of  our  own 
time.  The  article  is  directed  more  specially  against  Gentile.  The 
author's  main  point  is  that  there  is  an  uneliminated  realism  in  all  these 
doctrines  which  prevents  any  of  them  from  being  really  an  "absolute  " 
idealism.  Even  Gentile  is  not  really  an  "absolute"  idealist  since  he 
has  to  admit  the  existence  of  the  conscious  subject  which,  according  to 
him,  cannot  be  an  "  object"  of  consciousness.  Hence  if  his  theory  of 
knowledge  is  true,  his  metaphysical  doctrine  that  the  "transcendent" 
does  not  exist  must  be  false.  The  author's  own  position  is  that  the  subject 
is  not  "  transcendent  ".  I  have  a  direct  awareness  of  my  own  mental  life. 
All  attempts  to  make  consciousness  the  activity  of  a  "transcendent" 
universal  mind  or  of  a  consciousness  which  cannot  be  a  known  object  to 
itself  are  invalid.  I  could  wish  the  question  whether  the  kind  of  immedi- 
ate awareness  we  have  of  ourselves  is  the  same  as  that  which  we  have  of 
anything  else  had  been  more  fully  discussed,  and  also  that  it  had  been 
made  clearer  whether  this  awareness  is  supposed  to  be  knowledge  or  to  be 
the  foundation  of  knowledge.]  Q.  della  Valle.  I  metodi  della  Teoriadel 
Valore.  [How  do  we  come  to  know  the  various  values  of  ethics,  art,  etc.  ? 
Not  by  a  metaphysical  deduction  ;  they  are  much  more  certain  than  any 
metaphysical  theory.  Nor  by  a  theological  deduction ;  for  God  is  a 
hypothesis  constructed  on  the  basis  of  antecedently  known  values.  (This, 
by  the  way  seems  to  the  writer  of  this  notice  glaringly  false.)  Nor  by 
deduction  from  the  concept  of  reason  as  the  end.  Nor  yet  by  induction 
from  facts ;  this  would  lead  to  no  absolute  and  objective  values.  Value 
is  a  fact  apprehended  by  direct  introspection.  Hence  any  theory  of 
values  must  be  founded  on  psychological  analysis.  This  analysis  must 
not  be  a  mere  description  but  must  be  analogous  to  the  Kantian  analysis 
of  knowledge.  Kant's  criticism,  is,  in  fact,  the  first  step  to  a  more 
general  theory  of  values,  since  knowledge  is  only  one  among  a  vast 
plurality  of  different  and  incommensurable  values.]  Reviews,  etc.  Anno 


PHILOSOPHICAL   PEEIODICALS.  249 

iv.,  Fasc.  3,  July- September,  1921.  L.  Rougier.  Le  mythe  de  la 
"jRa&on"  et  la  Science  des  structures  mentales.  [An  attack  on  the 
validity  of  non-empirical  science  of  every  kind.  The  author  does  not  spare 
even  the  principles  of  logic,  which,  are  only  rigidly  valid  ' '  for  those  who 
please  to  construct  that  very  special  form  of  thought,  a  deductive  theory," 
They  only  appear  late  in  the  history  of  thought,  etc.,  etc.  Henri  Beyle 
could  never  understand  elementary  algebra.  We  must  therefore  get  rid 
of  our  superstition  about  logic  and  replace  it  by  a  comparative  study  of 
the  "  mental  structures  "  of  different  lands  and  ages.]  V.  Miceli.  La 
scienza  generate  del  diritto.  [The  author  repeats  his  former  contention 
that  there  can  be  no  such  thing  as  a  "  philosophy  of  law  ".  What  is  pos- 
sible is  a  study  of  existing  law  in  its  relation  to  social  life.  This  is  neither 
pure  jurisprudence  nor  pure  sociology,  but  something  between  the  two. 
It  has  to  consider,  e.g.,  not  merely  what  is  ethically  just,  but  which  of  the 
obligations  of  justice  may  usefully  be  enforced  by  law  in  a  given  society. 
Hence  it  cannot  be  created  simply  on  a  basis  of  ethics.]  E.  di  Carlo.  La 
possibilita  della  filosofia  del  diritto.  [A  reply  to  Miceli.  M.  argues 
that  law  is  an  empirical  fact,  therefore  there  can  be  no  philosophy  of  law. 
Why  does  he  not  apply  the  same  argument  to  prove  the  impossibility  of 
Ethics?  M.'s  own  treatment  of  law  is  itself  "philosophical".]  Q.  H. 
Bushnell.  Midian.  [In  support  of  the  theory  that  Moses  derived  his 
religion  from  Midian ;  the  philological  arguments  strike  a  non-specialist 
as  nighty  and  the  attempt  to  make  Hebrew  religion  " phallic"  as 
ludicrous.]  R.  Pavese.  Desiderio  di  sapere  e  misondisme.  ["  Miso- 
neism  "  has  a  high  social  importance  as  inhibitory  of  our  native  curiosity. 
Its  function  is  to  prevent  hasty  acceptance  of  novel  hypotheses  and  the 
immoral  exploitation  of  "  new  ideas  "  for  egoistic  ends.]  A.  Aliotta.  La 
nuova  filosofia  dell'  esperienza.  [The  "neutral"  monism  of  the  latest 
realism  does  not  really  do  away  with  the  "vicious  circle"  of  the  old 
empiricism  which  "new  realism  "  is  trying  to  avoid.  It  is,  e.g.,  absurd  to 
attempt  to  derive  subject  and  object  from  a  process  of  adaptation  to 
environment,  as  Avenarius  does.  The  duality  which  was  to  be  got  rid  of 
is  already  presupposed  when  we  speak  of  the  organism  and  its  environment. 
Actual  experience  always  exhibits  subject  and  object  together.  It  is  un- 
meaning to  assert  the  independence  of  either  or  to  derive  experience  from 
something  which  has  not  this  character  of  duality  in  unity.  The  reality  of 
time  is  experience  itself.  But  "real  duration  "  is  not  simply  a  continuous 
flow  ;  it  involves  also  the  recognition  of  the  identity  and  the  distinctness 
of  the  different  moments.  Similarly  the  contrast  of  myself  with  others  is 
implicit  in  every  moment  of  real  experience.  Experience  is  not  only  con- 
crete thought  but  also  action  creative  of  new  forms  of  being.  Experiment, 
action,  "try  and  try  again,"  is  the  only  method  both  of  science  and 
philosophy.]  Q.  della  Valle.  Le  caratteristiche  essenziali  del  Valore. 
[Value  is  indefinable,  but  we  can  specify  characters  which  belong  to  all 
values.  A  value  must  be  a  conscious  state  ;  it  must  be  the  result  of  a 
free  mental  activity  limited  by  universal  and  absolute  rules.  It  is  not 
necessary  that  every  value  should  be  actually  realised.  The  creation  of 
value  is  the  fundamental  task  of  the  spirit  by  which  it  transforms  chaos 
into  an  ordered  world.  The  specific  activity  by  which  values  are  created 
is  intuition,  an  "irreducible  "  activity  which  is  neither  rational,  emotional 
nor  volitional.]  Reviews. 

REVUE  NEO-SCOLASTIQUE  DE  I'HILOSOPHIE.  xxiii  Anne"e.  No.  01. 
August,  1921.  E.  Merschir,  S.J.  Berkeley  est-il  empiriste  ou  spiritual- 
iste  ?  [The  author's  answer  to  the  question  is  that  Berkeley  is  both  in 
virtue  of  his  principle  that  esse  =  percipere  aut  percipi.  All  attempts  to 
suppress  either  half  of  this  principle  falsify  B.'s  thought.  B.'s  philosophy 


"250  PHILOSOPHICAL   PEKIODICALS. 

remains  all  through  a  dualism,  and  the  reason  of  this  is  that  he  is  not 
critical  enough  ;  he  has  too  na'if  a  faith  in  human  intelligence.  A  well- 
informed,  appreciative,  and  thoughtful  essay.  But  is  B.'s  admission  of  a 
duality  (that  of  "  ideas  "  and  "  notions  ")  really  a  dualism  F]  E.  Janssens. 
Reponse  a  un  plaidoyer  probabiliste.  [Continues  the  criticisms  of  the 
author's  former  article  on  probabilism  with  special  reference  to  the  reply 
of  P.  Harmignie.j  A.  Bourgssonie.  Les  Principes  de  la  Raison.  [Con- 
clusion. Discusses  the  principles  of  causality,  natural  law,  "  parcimony," 
•"  teleology/'  "  type,"  "good".]  A.  Pelzer.  Les  Version  latines  d'Aris- 
tote.  [Notes  on  the  authorship  of  the  versions  of  the  Ethica  Nicomachea, 
Ethica  Eudemia,  Magna  Moralia,  De  Virtutibus  <  t  Vitiis  current  in  the 
thirteenth  century.]  Notices  of  Books.  No.  92.  November,  1921. 
Q.  Legrand.  Philosophic  et  sociologie  juridique.  [Traces  the  way  in 
which  the  general  philosophical  tendencies  of  different  ages  show  them- 
selves in  jurisprudence  with  special  reference  to  the  thirteenth  century, 
the  age  of  the  French  Revolution  and  the  nineteenth  century.]  E. 
Janssens.  Reponse  a  un  plaidoyer  probabiliste  (conclusion).  [A  con- 
tinuation of  the  author's  former  article  criticising  "  probabilism  "  as  a 
principle  of  casuistry.]  A.  Pelzer.  Les  versions  latines  des  ouvrages 
de  morale  conserves  sous  le  nom  d'Aristote  en  usage  au  xiiie  siecle. 
[Deals  with  the  translation  of  the  Nicomachean  Ethics  and  the  Byzantine 
commentaries  on  that  work  attributed  to  Robert  Grosseteste.  The  attribu- 
tion is  amply  justified.  It  is  certain  that  the  versions  were  not  made  by 
William  of  Morbeke,  and  the  Henri  Krosbein  or  Kosbein  to  whom  they 
•are  sometimes  assigned  is  probably  a  purely  imaginary  person.  Grosseteste 
supplements  his  renderings  by  rather  full  comments  on  the  etymology  and 
meaning  of  many  of  Aristotle's  technical  terms.  It  is  probably  through 
•his  version  that  information  of  this  kind  reached  St.  Thomas  and  Albertus 
Magnus.  This  has  been  often  overlooked  by  those  who  have  thought  that 
St.  Thomas's  knowledge  on  such  points  shows  acquaintance  with  the  Greek 
•commentators.]  M.  de  Wulf.  La  philosophie  de  maitre  Eckhart.  A. 
Bacci.  Philosophie  et  poesie  dans  le  poeme  de  Dante.  Reviews,  etc. 

RIVISTA  DI  FILOSOITA  (Organo  della  Societa  Filosofica  Italiana^.  Year 
xiii.,  No.  2.  April-June,  1921.  L.  Valli.  Lo  Spirito  filosofico  delle 
•grandi  stirpi  umane.  [The  author's  main  thesis  is  that  the  critical  spirit 
from  which  all  philosophy  springs  is  peculiarly  "  Aryan  ".  An  interesting 
essay,  but  what  about  the  facts  ?  It  is  assumed  that  Indian  mysticism  is 
a  purely  "  Aryan  "  development.  Is  this  certain  ?  The  Achaeans  are 
credited  with  introducing  the  Greek  language  and  the  critical  spirit  into 
Hellas.  What  of  the  facts  which  seem  to  show  that  the  lonians,  the  ad- 
mitted creators  of  "science,"  were  almost  wholly  of  the  old  "Mediter- 
ranean "  stock  ?  Much  stress  is  laid  on  the  practice  of  cremation  by 
"  Aryans  ".  But  surely  burial  was  as  usual  in  Greece  in  historic  times  as 
•cremation.]  E.  Buonaiuti.  Filosofie  e  religione  nella  cultura  con- 
temporanea.  [A  brief  address  to  the  recent  philosophical  Congress  at 
Rome.  The  main  point  is  that  the  attempts  of  the  "  immanence  "  and  other 
philosophies  to  find  a  substitute  for  God  is  a  failure.  Our  age  is  'in  transi- 
tion to  a  renewal  of  Christian  experience.  Hence  the  relative  value  of 
pragmatism  as  an  assertion  that  life  is  based  on  a  faith  which  is  prior  to 
all  "  dialectical"  justification  of  itself.]  A.  Pagano.  L'intuizione  intel- 
lettuale  come  momento  dell'  atto  del  giudizio.  [The  "intuition"  of  reality 
is  not  a  separate  mental  act  which  precedes  and  is  presupposed  by  judg- 
ment ;  it  is  immanent  in  the  most  elementary  judgment  and  can  be  dis- 
covered there  by  analysis.]  F.  A.  Ferrari.  Molteplicita  di  direttive  e 
unita  di  progresso  nella  storia  di  filosofia.  Critical  notes.  B.  Jakorenko. 
Lajilosojia  del  Bolscevismo.  ["  Bolshevism  "  is  treated  as  a  great  mani- 


I 


PHILOSOPHICAL  PEBIODICALS.  251 

festation  of  the  Russian  spirit  bound  to  lead  to  great  philosophical  de- 
velopments. It  is  not  mentioned  that  the  Bolshevist  Camarilla  is  mostly 
Hebrew.]  Q.  Capone=Braga.  Gli  errori  dell'  esperienza  internet,  secondo 
Condillac.  B.  Varisco.  II  valore  spirituale  della  vittoria.  E.  di 
Carlo.  La  c'risi  dell'  idealismo  assoluto.  Reviews,  etc. 

REVUE  DE  PHILOSOPHIE.  September-October,  1921.  H.  Quetton. 
Sainte  Catherine  de  Genes  et  I' element  Mystique  de  la  Religion.  [A 
study  of  Baron  von  Hiigel's  book,  The  Mystical  Elements  of  Religion,  etc. 
This  first  article  consists  of  a  sketch  of  the  life  of  St.  Catharine  of  Genoa 
whom  von  Hiigel  takes  as  a  type  of  the  true  mystic.]  Pedro  Descoqs. 
La  Theorie  de  la  Matiere  et  de  la  Forme,  et  ses  fondements.  [The  first  of 
an  important  series  of  articles  on  the  present  status  of  the  theory  of 
Hylomorphism.  The  writer  believes  (with  P.  Sertillanges)  that  Matter 
and  Form,  and  not  Actus  and  Potentia,  is  the  foundation  of  the  Thomist 
system.  After  separating  the  essential  from  the  unessential  in  the  theory, 
he  shows  that  the  old  proof  from  the  occurrence  of  substantial  change  in 
the  inorganic  world,  which  was  once  considered  sufficient  by  itself,  can  no 
longer  bs  looked  upon  as  valid,  since  such  substantial  changes  cannot  be 
assumed  to  occur.]  Emile  Catzeflis.  Spiritiialisme  et  Materialisme. 
[An  elaboration  of  the  proof  that  the  First  Cause  must  possess  the  attri- 
butes of  Liberty  and  Consciousness,  and  must  in  consequence  be  a  Spirit- 
ual Being.]  November-December,  1921.  Jacques  Chevalier.  Morale  et 
Metaphysique.  [This  is  the  paper  read  by  the  author  at  the  Oxford  Con- 
gress of  1920 ;  to  the  paper  are  subjoined  his  answers  to  the  criticisms 
proposed  during  the  discussion.  He  argues  that  the  notion  of  morality, 
which  is  possessed  by  all  men,  implies  the  recognition  of  an  ideal  and  an 
imperative  ;  and  that  these  in  turn  imply  the  existence  of  a  Supreme  Good, 
Who  is  the  Supreme  Legislator  and  Whose  Law  is  the  law  of  our  nature.] 
Paul  Vignon.  Pour  hater  la  rentree  en  scene  de  I'lde'e  en  biologie  trans- 
formiste  (ler  article).  [The  writer  wishes  to  see  acknowledged  by  biologists 
a  pre-existent  plan  in  accordance  with  which  evolution  is  being  worked  out. 
He  rejects  as  insufficient  the  theory  of  transformism  by  small  mutations, 
even  when  helped  by  natural  selection,  and  also  the  theory  of  saltations,  if 
these  are  assumed  to  occur  by  chance.]  Pedro  Descoqs.  Latheorie  de  la 
Matiere  et  de  la  Forme,  et  ses  fondements  (2e  article).  [In  this  article  the 
writer  considers  the  instance  of  substantial  change  which  occurs  in  nutrition. 
He  shows  that  the  reality  of  prima  materia  cannot  be  proved  therefrom 
unless  the  (Scotist)  theory  of  multiplicity  of  subordinated  forms  is  ex- 
cluded. Such  an  exclusion,  he  argues,  has  not  been  effected  by  any  of  the 
arguments  hitherto  advanced,  either  a  priori  or  a  posteriori.  Hence  sub- 
stantial change  in  the  Scholastic  sense  cannot  be  used  as  the  basis  for  a 
certain  proof  of  Hylomorphism.  If  this  theory  is  to  be  raised  above  the 
plane,  of  a  physical  hypothesis  it  must  be  disengaged  from  these  physical 
supports  and  made  to  rest  on  a  metaphysical  foundation.  This  is  to  be 
attempted  in  the  next  article.]  H.  Guetton.  Sainte  Catherine  de  Genes 
et  Velement  mystique  de  la  religion  (dernier  article).  [This  article  follows 
Baron  v.  Hiigel  in  his  discussion  of  St.  Catharine's  doctrine,  her  psychical 
states,  the  characteristic  tendencies  of  a  mystic,  and  the  relation  of  mystic- 
ism to  philosophy,  the  problem  of  evil,  and  pantheism.  "  Baron  von 
Hiigel  has  definitely  shown  that  mysticism  is  not  a  defect  but  a  most  in- 
timate communion  of  the  soul  with  God,  and  that  the  mystics,  far  from 
being  malades,  are  to  be  counted  .  .  .  among  the  greatest  benefactors  of 
the  human  race."]  O.  Habert.  Nouveau  conceptualisme,  apropos  d'un 
lime,  recent.  [M.  Emile  Meyerson  (author  of  the  book  referred  to)  is  here 
said  to  regard  scientific  theories  as  mental  schemes  imposed  on  Nature 
and  to  contrast  the  static  and  general  character  of  concepts  with  the 


252  PHILOSOPHICAL  PEEIODICALS. 

dynamic  and  individual  existence  of  things.  The  writer  of  the  article  re- 
states the  Thomistic  theory  of  conception,  substance,  and  individuation 
as  the  reconciliation  of  these  antinomies.] 

INTERNATIONAL  JOURNAL  OF  ETHICS,  xxxii.,  1.  October,  1921.  B.  M. 
Laing.  '  Aspects  of  the  Problem  of  Sovereignty.'  [Outlines  rise  of  the 
idea  of  unity  as  the  fundamental  characteristic  of  the  State,  and  of  or- 
ganisations within  society  now  opposed  to  the  State's  claim  to  sovereignty  ; 
suggests  that  certain  conditions  compel  the  State  to  claim  sovereignty, 
while  others  may  demand  freedom  for  other  social  organisations  ;  hence 
the  core  of  the  problem  appears  to  be  the  determination  of  the  objective 
conditions  which  determine  policy.]  Rupert  Clendon  Lodge.  '  Plato  arid 
the  Moral  Standard. '  [Examines  critically  Plato's  views  as  to  the  stand- 
ard applied  by  the  philosophic  judge  to  questions  of  ethical  value  ;  shows 
that  many  of  the  various  criteria  mentioned  by  Plato  have  only  a  limited 
application  ;  leads  to  question  '  is  a  given  character  in  touch  with  objective 
reality  or  not  ? ']  John  Dashiell  Stoops.  '  The  Will  and  the  Instinct 
of  Sex. '  [Maintains  that  growth  of  powerful  emotional  complex  is  due  to 
dissociation  of  instinct  and  will ;  suggests  that  through  sublimation  we 
need  to  find  in  the  instincts  both  the  ends  and  the  energy  of  the  will.] 
M.  C.  Otto.  'The  Moral  Education  of  Youth.'  [Shows  that  the  real 
task  is  not  that  of  teaching  abstract  rules  but  of  developing  a  moral  atti- 
tude to  actual  situations  ;  criticises  attempts  to  do  this  by  moral  instruc- 
tion and  suggests  the  importance  of  other  methods.]  Ethel  E.  Sabin. 
'  Mistaking  America.'  [Criticises  and  replies  to  article  by  J.  O.  P.  Bland 
who  maintained  that  America  is  sentimental,  dominated  by  feminine 
ideals.]  Frank  Chapman  Sharp.  'Is  there  a  Universally  Valid  Moral 
Standard  ? '  [Maintains  that  there  is — the  production  of  the  maximum  of 
good  attainable  under  the  conditions — analyses  causes  for  deviations  from 
the  impartial  standpoint.] 


VIIL— NOTES. 
DR.  LUTOSLAWSKI'S  "THEORY  OF  PERSONALITY". 

2  VIA  CROCIFISSALTO, 
SBTTIGNANO-FIBENZE,  22nd  January,  1922. 

SIR, 

Dr.  Lutoslawski  in  "  A  Theory  of  Personality  "  tells  that  in  his 
experience,  as  in  the  spiritual  experience  of  many  others,  the  conviction 
of  immortality  had  been  a  sudden  revelation  corning  after  years  of  mere 
thinking  on  this  matter,  and  of  believing  the  testimony  of  others.  The 
views  of  others  had  not  seemed  definitively  convincing  but  then  came  the 
revelation  which  gave  immediate  intuitive  certainty.  I  myself  once  had 
an  experience  of  this  sort  though  not  concerned  with  immortality,  and  an 
account  of  what  then  and  subsequently  happened  may  be  of  interest  to 
philosophers. 

I  was  at  that  moment,  in  consequence  of  some  psychological  observation, 
led  to  think  a  great  deal  about  the  antinomy  of  rest  and  motion,  and  I  was 
trying  to  work  out  a  theory  concerning  this.  My  occupation  with  this  had 
become  so  intense  that  for  a  week  I  had  not  gone  to  bed  at  all,  but  in  the 
intervals  of  speculation  I  used  to  nap  for  short  pariods  before  the  fire. 
At  last  there  came  the  moment  when  the  antinomy  resolved  itself  com- 
pletely, not  as  a  theory  but  as  a  revelation.  The  universe  was  there  about 
me  as  a  coherent  consistent  whole.  My  own  harmony  and  identification 
with  it  was  as  complete  as  its  own  inner  coherence.  I  was  whate'er  I 
thought  on  and  my  thoughts  went  everywhere.  I  was  mountain  hill  or 
stream,  bird  beast  or  fish,  ravening  shark  or  sea-shouldering  whale,  all 
things  and  everything. 

I  do  not  know  how  long  this  state  lasted.  When  the  vision,  the  feeling 
of  that  which  absolutely  and  completely  was,  had  gone,  I  tried  to 
measure  the  value  of  that  which  was  left  over.  Not  at  once,  of  course. 
For  the  moment  the  vision  splendid,  and  the  void  its  disappearance 
caused,  were  all  my  concern.  But  afterwards  I  found  that  its  results  were 
solid  gain.  Of  course  I  was  not  left  with  a  satisfactory  theory.  My 
revelation  had  transcended  theory  and  could  not  be  translated  back  into  the 
lesser  medium.  I  had  no  theory  but  I  had  knowledge  which  was  gold 
beside  the  theory's  silver. 

So  it  continued  for  some  time,  a  year  or  more,  but  one  day  as  I  was 
meditating  upon  this,  I  came  to  have  suspicions  of  a  weak  link  in  the  chain 
of  process  which  had  given  me  my  greater  truth.  It  seemed  to  me  that 
what  I  had  done  was  exactly  what  the  artist  does  when  he  creates,  and 
that  the  validity  of  my  creation  was  akin  to  the  validity  of  poem  or 
picture.  The  artist,  as  I  then  expressed  it,  comes  to  an  equilibrium  in 
the  face  of  a  particular  situation,  while  the  mystic  comes  to  an  equilibrium 
in  the  face  of  a  total  situation.  In  both  cases  the  preliminary  work  of 
gathering  and  meditating  is  checked  by  the  inadequacy  of  the  material  so 


254  NOTES. 

taken,  to  satisfy  the  worker's  needs.  He  cannot  so  bring  the  process  to  a 
satisfactory  conclusion.  The  "  will "  to  form  the  stuff  is  there,  and  if  the 
stuff  is  malleable  the  form  is  given.  The  thing  as  thus  reformed  is  then 
found,  and  seems  then  like  an  absolute  discovery.  It  is  as  though  one 
were  expanding  a  balloon  with  the  breath  of  one's  lungs  and  failing  in  the 
effort,  at  least  in  appearance,  but  that  at  last,  when  one  has  either  in 
despair  abandoned  it,  or  in  final  effort  lost  consciousness  of  it,  the  balloon 
ascends,  and  we  discover  it,  revealed  to  us  in  the  heavens.  It  looks  like 
a  balloon,  it's  located  like  a  balloon,  it  certainly  is  a  balloon,  and  as  it  was 
previously  shown  that  we  could  not  blow  up  a  balloon,  it  cannot  be  the 
balloon  that  we  were  at  work  upon.  None  the  less  I  think  it  is.  In  this 
way  was  faith  in  my  revelation  weakened,  and  my  faith  in  all  other 
revelations  as  well.  Since  then  I  think  that  verification  is  necessary  to 
make  convincing  my  own  revelations,  and  I  am  not  inclined  to  value  the 
unsupported  ones  of  other  people  at  a  higher  rate. 

The  essential  mechanism  of  revelation  is,  I  believe,  that  of  all  imagery 
formation.  Imagery  is  the  correlative  of  emotion.  I  believe  that  imagery 
is  related  to  emotion  somewhat  as  "  sensation  "  is  to  "  feeling  ".  I  find 
that  "sensations,"  when  so  taken  together  that  the  value  is  of  the 
togetherness  and  not  of  the  particular  "  sensation,"  constitute  "  feeling  ". 
This  feeling  may  exist  independently  of  any  definite  sensation  or  sensory 
object,  or  subordinate  to  such  an  one.  In  like  wise  I  find  that  when  there 
is  a  stimulus  to  action,  whether  the  action  of  thinking  or  some  other, 
which  cannot  unfold  itself  so  rapidly  as  the  stimuli  accumulate,  then  there 
follows  the  formation  of  images  and  emotions,  images  in  so  far  as  the  sub- 
stitute for  action  finds  a  focal  point,  and  emotion  in  so  far  as  it  does  not. 
Here  again  there  may  be  merely  diffused  emotion,  or  the  emotion  may  be 
subordinate  to  imagery.  A  "  revelation  "  is  such  a  focus  when  it  is  com- 
prehensive enough,  what  I  called  above  a  total  situation.  It  is  singularly 
convincing  because  the  interest  in  it  is  so  great,  and  because  its  compre- 
hensiveness makes  it  difficult  to  circumvent.  It  persists  if  it  is  the  kind 
of  thing  that  we  continue  to  want. 

It  is  furthermore  u  true  "  in  the  sense  in  which  "  Beauty  is  truth,  truth 
beauty,"  that  is,  the  situation  has  the  quality  of  a  felt  coherence.  If  it 
were  possible  to  have  a  proposition  durably  as  comprehensive  as  this  situa- 
tion, that  proposition  would  also  be  "  true ".  But  even  the  mystics 
admit  that  no  such  proposition  is  possible.  Their  ultimate  truth  is  being, 
not  affirmation.  Any  proposition  gains  its  truth  value  from  the  felt 
situation,  and  when  the  felt  situation  is  more  comprehensive  than  the  pro- 
position, the  proposition  is  not  really  equivalent  to  it  and  may  be  false. 
It  can  have  then  the  value  of  hypothesis,  and  it  can  have  nothing  more. 

P.S. — This  relation  of  emotion  and  image  explains  the  Aristotelian 
catharsis.  The  diffused  emotions  of  fear  and  pity  are  replaced  by  the 
tragic  imagery.  The  purgation  is  the  more  complete  because  of  the 
effective  canalisation  afforded  by  the  tragic  evolution  from  beginning 
through  middle  to  end. 

The  tragic  purgation  when  really  effective,   has  the   character   of  a 
temporary  conversion.      Revelations,   on  the  other   hand,  dealing  with 
situations  more  or  less  total,  often  produce  a  permanent  catharsis.    This 
is  excellently  put  in  words  by  Dante  when  Beatrice  says  : 
"  lo  son  fatta  da  Dio,  sua  merce,  tale, 
Che  la  vostra  miseria  non  mi  tange, 
Ne  fiamma  d'esto  incendio  non  m'assale."  l 

1  "  I  am  made  such  by  God,  in  his  grace,  that  your  misery  does  not  touch 
me  ;  nor  the  flame  of  this  burning  assail  me." — (Carlyle.) 


NOTES.  255 

Both  fear  and  pity  have  been  purged  away  and  love  purified  remains  the 
only  motive. 

It  is  hardly  necessary  to  add  that  what  is  true  of  tragedy  and  the 
emotions  of  fear  and  pity  is  equally  true  for  other  qualities  of  art  expres- 
sion, and  other  interests  in  revelation  and  conversion. 

LEO  STEIN. 

A  CORRECTION. 

MR.  W.  E.  JOHNSON  has  pointed  out  to  me  that  on  page  7  of  my  Hertz 
Lecture  on  "  Universals  and  Propositions,"  I  have  misrepresented  him  and 
even  reversed  his  meaning.  He  says  that  he  gave  a  flash  of  lightning  not 
as  an  instance  of  a  substance  but  of  what  is  not  a  substance.  I  am  glad  to 
find  that  it  is  so  and  I  regret  the  misunderstanding.  There  now  remains 
no  point  of  importance  in  which  I  disagree  with  Mr.  Johnsou's  book  ex- 
cept his  account  of  what  constitutes  generality.  Perhaps  the  difference 
even  here  may  turn  out  to  be  less  fundamental  than  it  seems. 

G.  F.  STOUT. 
SCHULE  DER  GEISTESKUNDE. 

HERR  STAAK  of  Bernitt,  near  Biitzow  (Mecklenburg)  writes  to  the  Uni- 
versity of  Manchester  expressing  his  desire  to  enlist  the  co-operation  of 
English  scholars  in  establishing  a  '  Schule  der  Geisteskunde, '  concerned 
especially  with  higher  mental  development.  He  published  at  the  begin- 
ning of  last  year  a  chapter  of  his  investigations^  called  '  Aufbau  der 
hoheren  geistigen  Entwickelung, '  and  he  offers  to  place  ten  gratuitous 
copies  at  the  disposal  of  scholars  in  this  country,  who  are  interested  in  the 
project. 

,        MIND  ASSOCIATION. 

THE  Annual  Meeting  of  the  Mind  Association  will  be  held  this  year  in 
Manchester,  at  the  University  Arts  Building,  at  5  p.m.  on  Friday,  14th 
July. 

A  Joint  Session  of  the  Association  with  the  Aristotelian  Society  and 
the  British  Psychological  Society  has  been  arranged  to  take  place  in  Man- 
chester from  14th  to  17th  July.  Most  of  the  papers  read  at  this  Session 
will,  in  accordance  with  a  resolution  passed  at  the  last  annual  meeting,  be 
published  in  the  October  number  of  MIND.  Any  member  of  the  Associa- 
tion may  attend  the  Meetings  and,  on  paying  a  fee  of  5s.,  will  be  supplied 
in  advance  with  off-prints  of  the  papers.  Accommodation  will  be  provided 
for  men  at  Hulme  Hall,  and  for  women  at  Ashburne  Hall.  The  charge 
for  this  from  Friday  dinner  to  Monday  breakfast  (inclusive)  will  be  27s. 
For  partial  attendance  the  charges  will  be  :  Bedroom  and  Breakfast, 
6s.  6d.  per  day ;  Lunch,  Is.  6d.  ;  Tea,  6d.  ;  Dinner,  3s.  6d.  All  meals 
will  be  at  Hulme  Hall,  except  that  breakfast  will  be  at  Ashburne  Hall 
for  those  staying  there. 

Members  who  wish  to  take  part  in  the  Session  are  requested  to  apply 
as  early  as  possible  to 

Prof.  S.  Alexander, 

24  Brunswick  Road, 

Withington,  Manchester, 

enclosing,  with  their  application,  the  fee  of  5s.,  if  they  wish  to  have  off- 
prints, and  stating  what  accommodation  (if  any)  they  require  in  Hulme 


256  NOTES. 

•or  Ashburne  Hall.     The  charge  for  accommodation  should  not  be  enclosed 
with  the  application,  but  paid  to  the  Bursar  on  leaving. 
The  Programme  of  Meetings  is  as  follows  : — 

FRIDAY,  UTH  JULY. 

At  5  p.m.     At  the  University  Arts  Building.     Annual  Meeting  of 

the  Mind  Association. 
At  9  p.m.     At  Hulme  Hall. 

"  Symbolism  as  a  Basis  for  Metaphysics."  The  Bishop  of  Man- 
chester. 

SATURDAY,  15xn  JULY. 

At  10  a.m.     At  the  University  Arts  Building. 

Symposium:  "Are  History  and  Science  different  kinds  of 
Knowledge  ? "  R.  G.  Collingwood,  A.  E.  Taylor  and  F.  0.  S. 
Schiller. 

At  10  a.m.  and  2.30  p.m.     At  the  University   Psychological  La- 
boratory.    Demonstrations  and  Papers. 
At  9  p.m.     At  Hulme  Hall. 

Symposium:  "Is  the  Unconscious  a  Conception  of  Value  in 
Psychology  ? "  G.  C.  Field,  F.  Aveling,  and  J.  Laird. 

.SUNDAY,  16TH  JULY.     At  Hulme  Hall. 

At  2  p.m?    Symposium:    "The  Relation   between   Sentiments  and 

Complexes".     W.  H.   R.  Rivers,  A.  G.  Tansley,  T.  H.  Pear, 

Bernard  Hart,  A.  F.  Shand  and  C.  S.  Myers. 
At  5  p.m.     "Mr.  Alexander's  Theory  of  Sense  Perception".     G.  F. 

Stout. 
At  9  p.m.     Discussion  on  "  The  Philosophical  Aspects  of  the  Principle 

of  Relativity  ".     To  be  opened  by  A.  N.  Whitehead. 


VOL.  xxxi.     No.   123.]  DULY,   1922, 


MIND 


A  QUARTERLY  REVIEW 

OF 

PSYCHOLOGY  AND  PHILOSOPHY 


L— THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  CHANCE. 

BY  F.  Y.  EDGEWOETH. 

NEAELY  forty  years  have  elapsed  since  I  contributed  to 
MIND,  under  the  title  now  again  employed,  some  reflections 
suggested  by  Dr.  Venn's  Logic  of  Chance.  The  appearance 
of  another  original  work,  inquiring  into  first  principles  and 
challenging  received  opinions,  Mr.  Maynard  Keynes'  treatise 
on  Probability,  now  renders  opportune  a  reconsideration  of 
views  expressed  in  1884. 

The  questions  to  be  rehandled  may  be  arranged  under  the 
following  heads : — 

I.  What  is  the  definition  of  Probability ;  what  does  Beflec- 
tion  (in  Locke's  sense)  reveal  respecting  that  sort  of  partial 
belief  to  which  the  term  Probability  relates  ? 

II.  Should  that  kind  of  belief  be  attached  to  propositions 
other  than  those  based  on  statistical  experience ;  on  the  ob- 
servation that  in  the  long  run  the  frequency  of  a  species  (e.g., 
male  births)  presents  approximately  a   certain  ratio  to  the 
frequency  of  its  genus  (e.g.,  births  in  general) ? 

III.  With  respect  to  probabilities  which  are  thus  based  on 
statistical    uniformities,    "series"    in    Dr.    Venn's    phrase, 
what  canons  are  available  for   proving  that  the  series  will 
hold  good  beyond  the  limits  within  which  it  has  been  ob- 
served ? 

IV.  What  is  the  bearing  of  the  Probability-Calculus  on 
conduct ;  what  guidance  is  afforded  by  that  compound   of 
prospective  advantage  and  the  probability  of  its  attainment 
which  is  technically  termed  Expectation  ? 

17 


258  F.  Y.  EDGE  WORTH: 

I.  CHARACTERISTICS  OF  PROBABILITY. 

Probability  seems  not  to  admit  of  definition.  "  We  can- 
not analyse  the  probability-relation  in  terms  of  simpler  ideas  " 
(Keynes,  p.  8).  It  is,  in  Locke's  phraseology,  a  simple  idea. 
Yet  it  is  not  so  simple  and  clear  but  that  doubts  about  its 
characteristics  have  arisen. 

First,  are  there  gradations  of  probability ;  can  we  measure 
degrees  of  belief?  I  am  not  concerned  to  defend  the 
numerical  precision  of  the  measurement.  We  may  be  con- 
tent with  the  conception  of  measurement  which  satisfies  the 
physicists.  As  Prof.  Love  writes  :  "  The  capacity  of  numbers 
to  answer  questions  of  how  many  and  how  much,  in  other 
words  to  express  the  results  of  counting  and  measuring,  may 
be  regarded  as  a  secondary  property  derived  from  the  more 
fundamental  one  of  expressing  order.  .  .  .  Natural  numbers 
form  a  series  with  a  definite  order,  and  the  expressions 
'  greater  than '  and  '  less  than '  mean  more  advanced  and  less 
advanced  in  this  order  "  (Article  on  "  Functions  of  Real  Vari- 
ables," Encyclopedia  Britannica,  edn.  x.,  p.  544,  vol.  28.  Com- 
pare Eddington,  Space,  Time  and  Gravitation,  quoted  in  part 
below).  In  short  the  issue  is  narrowed  to  the  question  whether 
it  is  always  possible  "  to  arrange  probabilities  in  an  order  of 
magnitude,"  to  say  that  one  is  greater  or  less  than  another 
(p.  29).  The  issue  thus  defined  is  not  affected  by  the  in- 
stances which  Mr.  Keynes  directs  against  the  possibility  of 
"reasoned  numerical  estimates  of  probability";  such  as  the 
case  of  the  vessel  Waratah  which  disappeared  in  Southern 
waters  and  the  estimate  of  the  chance  that  it  was  still  afloat 
after  a  considerable  lapse  of  time  (p.  23).  Even  the  most 
discriminating  of  our  senses,  eyesight,  often  affords  only 
blurred  and  vague  perceptions.  A  common  experience  was 
expressed  by  Euripides'  Antigone  when,  looking  from  the 
battlements  of  Thebes  at  one  of  the  invading  chiefs,  she 
said 

opw  8fJT  'ov  crcK^co?,  6pa)  Be  TTO)?.     (Phoenissce,  161.) 

From  a  similar  standpoint  Priam  might  discern  that  one 
hero  was  taller  than  another  without  being  able  to  form  a 
" reasoned  numerical  estimate"  of  their  heights.  But  Mr. 
Keynes  objects  to  even  rough  comparisons  between  proba- 
bilities unless  they  are  in  eodem  genere.  "It  is  not  always 
possible  to  say  that  the  degree  of  our  rational  belief  in 
one  conclusion  is  either  equal  to  greater  or  less  than  the 
degree  of  our  belief  in  another"  (p.  34).  The  case  is  illus- 
trated by  the  degrees  of  similarity  which  cannot  always  be 
placed  in  an  order  of  magnitude.  "  There  may  be  no  com- 


THE   PHILOSOPHY  OF   CHANCE.  259 

parison  between  the  degree  of  similarity  which  exists  be- 
tween books  bound  in  red  morocco  and  white  morocco  and 
books  bound  in  red  morocco  and  red  calf  "  (p.  36).  I  am 
disposed  fco  attach  importance  to  the  incident  that  in  the 
scale  of  probability  (whatever  the  subject)  there  is  at  least 
one  fixed  point  or  tract  between  complete  disbelief  and  per- 
fect certitude  ;  that  corresponding  to  hesitation  between  two 
courses  of  action  which  offer  equal  gain  there  are  comparable 
probabilities  of  its  attainment.  But  Mr.  Keynes  would  per- 
haps not  admit  these  objections  (p.  30). 

Supposing  that  different  amounts  of  belief  can  be  arranged 
in  a  scale,  does  this  presuppose  a  "  series  "  in  Dr.  Venn's 
sense?  Must  we  say  with  him  "the  greater  part  of  their 
meaning  and  certainly  their  only  justification  are  to  be 
sought  in  the  series  of  corresponding  events  to  which  they 
belong"  (Logic  of  Chance,  edn.  3,  p.  150)?  Must  we  say 
with  Ellis:  "  I  have  been  unable  to  sever  the  judgment  that 
one  event  is  more  likely  than  another  from  the  belief  that  in 
the  long  run  it  will  occur  more  frequently "  (quoted  by 
Keynes,  p.  93)  ?  Mr.  Keynes  argues  forcibly  against  this 
"frequency  theory":  which  even  when  purified  from  the 
assumption  of  numerical  precision  and  other  crudities  appears 
to  him  untenable.  Whereas  probability  is  always  relative 
to  definite  data,  if  the  datum  consists  of  a  "  class  of  refer- 
ence"— what  I  have  above  described  as  a  "genus" — how 
are  we  to  know  what  class  is  appropriate,  when  a  given  pro- 
position belongs  to  innumerable  different  classes  ?  I  under- 
stand the  difficulty  to  be  of  the  kind  which  Dr.  Venn  has 
illustrated  by  the  case  of  the  consumptive  Englishman  in 
Madeira.  Which  set  of  statistics  is  appropriate— those  re- 
lating to  Englishmen  in  general,  or  to  consumptive  patients 
without  respect  to  nationality  ?  So  it  may  happen  with  re- 
spect to  the  measurement  of  time  that  one  has  to  depend 
upon  two  clocks  neither  of  which  keeps  good  time.  Yet 
common-sense  may  conjecture  which  of  the  two,  or  what 
combination  of  the  two,  will  give  the  best  approximation  to 
the  true  time.  The  discrepancy  between  bad  clocks,  and 
that  more  embarrassing  discrepancy  between  the  best 
clocks  moved  through  space  at  different  rates  which  the 
Einstein  theory  discloses,  do  not  deter  the  physicist  from 
relying  on  his  chronometer.  Thus  Prof.  Eddington  testifies  : 
"  I  have  no  notion  of  time  except  as  the  measurement  with 
some  kind  of  clock  "  (Space,  Time  and  Gravitation,  p.  13). 
He  is  speaking,  I  think,  with  reference  to  the  deliberate 
judgments  of  science.  He  would  not  insist,  I  suppose,  that 
we  always  think  of  a  clock  in  connexion  with  estimates  of 


260  F.  Y.  EDGEWORTH: 

duration,  for  instance  when  we  hastily  judge  that  there  is  or 
is  not  time  to  cross  a  street  before  a  (<  taxi "  will  be  on  us. 
The  Sultan  who,  as  told  in  the  Spectator  (June  18,  1711), 
seemed  to  himself  to  have  lived  through  years  during  the 
few  moments  for  which  he  held  his  head  under  water  was 
not  estimating  the  lapse  of  time  by  any  objective  measure  of 
duration.  Dr.  Venn  allows  similar  exceptions  to  the  rule 
that  probability  implies  reference  to  a  series  (op.  cit.,  p.  152). 
The  exceptions  are  less  important  than  might  be  expected 
in  virtue  of  a  conception  of  which  Mr.  Keynes  has  not  made 
much  use,  that  of  "  Cross-series  "  (Venn,  op.  cit.,  pp.  147-148). 
"  We  are  very  seldom  called  upon  to  decide  and  act  upon  a 
single  contingency  which  cannot  be  viewed  as  being  one  of  a 
series."  "  A  man,  say,  buys  a  life  annuity,  insures  his  life  on 
a  railway  journey,  puts  into  a  lottery,  and  so  on."  It  may 
be  expected,  I  think,  that  the  class  of  actions  which  cannot 
be  regarded  as  part  of  a  "  series  "  will  diminish  with  the  in- 
crease of  providence  and  sympathy  (MiND,  loc.  cit.,  p.  224). 

From  considering  the  normal  character  of  belief  we  pass 
by  an  easy  transition  to  the  standard  and  tests  of  credibility. 
Probability,  as  Mr.  Keynes  rightly  insists,  is  ever  relative  to 
some  assumed  premisses.  A  premiss  may  be  subjective  such 
as  the  belief  in  one's  own  existence.  But  the  relation  be- 
tween the  premiss  and  what  may  with  more  or  less  proba- 
bility be  inferred  from  it  is  " rational"  or  "objective"  (pp. 
8, 16,  97,  et  passim}.  I  have  suggested  (MiND,  loc.  cit.,  p.  225), 
that  the  first  principles  of  credibility  are  like  those  of  conduct 
which  according  to  Mill  do  not  admit  of  proof  in  the  ordinary 
sense.  "Considerations  may  be  presented  capable  of  de- 
termining the  intellect  either  to  give  or  withhold  its  assent " 
(Utilitarianism,  p.  6,  cp.  p.  52).  I  must  leave  it  to 
philosophers  to  enounce  the  considerations  proper  to  the 
standard  of  credibility.  Perhaps  they  will  be  found  analogous 
to  Hume's  reflections  upon  The  Standard  of  Taste  :  showing 
that  amidst  "  the  great  variety  of  taste  as  well  as  of  opinion  " 
.  .  .  "there  are  certain  general  principles  .  .  .  whose  influ- 
ence a  careful  mind  may  trace  "  (Essays,  Green  and  Grose's 
edition,  Vol.  i.,  pp.  266,  271).  More  objective  judgments  no 
doubt  are  available  when  the  scale  of  probabilities  is  finely 
graduated  and  the  degrees  are  verified  by  observed  frequency 
of  occurrence. 

II.  A  PRIORI  PROBABILITY. 

Some  test  of  credibility  seems  to  be  required  when  we  go 
on  to  consider  the  legitimacy  of  probabilities  based  on  the 


THE   PHILOSOPHY  OF   CHANCE.  261 

so-called  principle  of  Sufficient  Reason  (which  Mr.  Keynes 
prefers  to  call  the  principle  of  "  Indifference ")  without 
statistical  verification  by  way  of  a  "  series  ".  I  have  con- 
tended that  Dr.  Venn  has  gone  too  far  in  his  scepticism  with 
respect  to  these  d  priori  probabilities.  This  contention  now 
derives  powerful  support  from  Mr.  Keynes'  dialectic.  He 
too  maintains  that  Dr.  Venn's  scepticism  goes  too  far  (Keynes, 
p.  52).  He  has  laid  down  rules  for  purifying  this  source  of 
belief  from  the  contradictions  and  anomalies  with  which  it 
has  been  mixed  (p.  61  and  context).  He  points  out  that  Dr. 
Venn  is  not  consistent  in  his  scepticism  (Keynes,  p.  100).  To 
the  passage  in  the  Logic  of  Chance  which  Mr.  Keynes  adduces 
I  may  add  the  following.  Seeking  an  analogue  for  the  sporadic 
distribution  of  digits  in  the  decimal  places  of  the  constant  TT, 
Dr.  Venn  supposes  that  we  have  a  rod  or  line  which  we  want 
to  measure  with  the  utmost  accuracy.  "  We  lay  our  rod 
against  the  scale  and  find  it,  say,  fall  between  31  and 
32  inches  ;  we  then  look  at  the  next  division  of  the  scale, 
viz.,  that  into  tenths  of  an  inch.  Can  we  see  the  slightest 
reason  why  the  number  of  these  tenths  should  be  other  than 
independent  of  the  number  of  whole  inches  ?  "  (op.  cit.,  p.  112. 
The  italics  are  mine.)  For  another  example,  "we  should 
expect  rather  than  otherwise  to  find  here  (in  a  square  root), 
as  in  the  case  of  TT,  that  incommensurability  and  resultant 
randomness  of  order  in  the  digits  was  the  rule,  and  com- 
mensurability  was  the  exception  "  (op.  cit,  p.  113).  Now  this 
sporadic  distribution  of  digits  is  just  the  sort  of  assumption 
which  I  have  postulated  under  the  designation  of  "  d  priori," 
or  better  "  unverified,"  probability  (cp.,  Article  on  Probability, 
Encyclopedia  Britannica,  edition  11,  §§  6,  132). 

The  principle  is  of  wide  application  in  Economics  and 
other  branches  of  Social  Science.  Thus  Prof.  Pigou  relies 
on  a  presumption  of  the  nature  of  "unverified  probability  " 
that  "  conclusions  about  the  effect  of  an  economic  cause  upon 
economic  welfare  will  hold  good  also  of  the  effect  on  total 
welfare"  (Wealth  and  Welfare,  p.  11).  In  a  recent  review 
of  Mr.  Keynes'  Probability  he  rests  on  the  same  sort  of 
evidence  the  assumption  that  "  curves  of  demand  and  supply 
are  likely  to  be  continuous,"  that  there  is  "  some  definite 
relation  between  the  elasticity  of  demand  at  a  point  taken 
as  known  and  the  elasticity  at  neighbouring  points  "  (Econo- 
mic Journal,  vol.  xxxi.  (1921),  p.  512).  I  have  submitted 
other  examples  in  several  numbers  of  the  Economic  Journal, 
to  which  references  may  be  found  in  the  Journal  of  the  Royal 
Statistical  Society  at  a  passage  in  which  I  point  out  that 
d  priori  probabilities  are  involved  in  a  generally  accepted 


262  F.   Y.   EDGEWOETH  : 

argument  concerning  the  distribution  of  velocities  in  a  medley 
of  colliding  molecules  (vol.  Ixxxiv.,  1921,  p.  81 ;  cp.,  1922, 
vol.  Ixxxv.,  p.  483). 

It  may  be  observed  that  in  general,  for  instance  in  all  the 
applications  which  have  just  been  noticed,  the  use  of  a  priori 
probabilities  has  no  connexion  with  inverse  probability. 
That  conjunction  does  occur  in  one  very  important  branch  of 
Probabilities — that  which  deals  with  errors-of-observation. 
As  Laplace  remarks  (Essai  Philosophique),  this  is  the  part  of 
our  science  which  involves  the  most  difficult  and  delicate 
analysis.  The  treatment  of  this  subject  was  one  of  the 
principal  objects  to  which  his  great  work,  The'orie  analytique 
des  probabilites  was  directed  (loc.  cit.}. 

A  very  simple  illustration  of  the  problems  involved  will  be 
sufficient  here.  Let  there  be  given  several  observations  each 
standing  for,  purporting  to  be,  the  measure  of  some  magnitude 
— such  as  a  distance  or  an  angle — which  it  is  required  to 
ascertain.  Thus  to  measure  a  required  length,  e.g.,  a  sur- 
veyor's base-line, 

X2        Xrt  Xx       X3 

X 

let  OXu  OX2  .  .  .  OXn  be  n  observations  numbered,  say,  in 
the  order  of  time  in  which  they  occurred.  It  is  required  to 
combine  these  observations  so  as  to  obtain  the  best  value  of 
OX  the  qucesitum. 

There  is  to  be  distinguished  the  special  case  (connected 
with  the  name  of  Bernoulli)  in  which  the  observations  stand 
(not  as  above  for  an  absolute  magnitude,  but)  for  a  ratio,  e.g., 
that  of  the  black  balls  to  all  the  balls  in  an  urn  containing 
only  black  and  white  balls.  Thus  OXj  might  stand  for  the 
percentage  of  black  balls  in  a  sample  numbering  a  hundred 
taken  at  random  from,  such  an  urn  (each  ball  being  returned 
to  the  urn  after  it  has  been  drawn,  unless  the  number  of 
balls  in  the  urn  is  indefinitely  great)  ;  OX2  would  stand  for 
the  percentage  presented  by  another  sample,  and  so  on.  It 
is  required  to  combine  these  observations  so  as  to  determine 
OX  the  ratio  of  black  to  white  balls  in  the  urn. 

It  is  commonly  taken  for  granted  that  a  priori  one  value 
of  OX  is  as  likely  to  be  the  true  value  as  any  other.  But 
there  may  sometimes  be  reason  for  doubting  this.  We  may 
know  beforehand  the  whereabouts  of  the  qucesitum  ;  in  which 
case  d  priori  equi-probability  could  only  be  predicated  of  a 
certain  tract  of  values,  say  a  portion  of  the  horizontal  line 
through  O.  A  more  exact  statement  is  given  below. 


THE   PHILOSOPHY  OF   CHANCE.  263 

In  the  shadowy  world  of  a  priori  probabilities  our  author 
has  made  some  remarkable  explorations  which  are  relevant 
to  the  problems  now  before  us.  First,  in  the  special  case 
above  distinguished,  he  argues  that  the  distribution  of  a  priori 
probabilities  is  not,  as  commonly  assumed  by  the  classical 
writers,  the  equi-probability  of  each  ratio,  but  that  of  each 
"  constitution  "  in  Boole's  sense  (p.  57).  It  follows  that  "  an 
approximately  equal  number  of  black  and  white  balls  is 
d  priori  more  probable  than  a  large  excess  of  one  colour" 
(p.  50;  cp.,  Boole,  Laws  of  Thought,  p.  370).  Again,  still 
with  reference  to  our  special  case,  c  being  a  character  com- 
pounded of  a  and  b  between  which  there  is  no  association,  if 
x  is  the  probability  of  a,  y  of  b,  #,  the  probability  of  c,  =  xy. 
Then  if  all  values  of  x  and  likewise  of  y  between  certain 
limits  are  equally  probable,  the  values  of  z  are  not  so  distri- 
buted (p.  381).  Likewise,  in  the  general  case,  if  one  variable, 
say  specific  volume,  has  its  values  equally  distributed  d  priori, 
then  a  variable  which  is  a  function  of  the  first  one,  say 
specific  density,  does  not  so  distribute  its  values  (pp.  45-46. 
Cp.,  Encyclopedia  Britannica,  Art.  Probability,  §  8). 

These  objections  to  commonly  made  assumptions  are  of 
considerable  philosophical  interest.  But  their  practical  im- 
portance with  reference  to  the  Theory  of  Errors  is  less  than 
might  be  supposed  for  more  than  one  reason. 

First,  when  the  magnitude  for  whose  various  values  we 
claim  equal  probability  is  very  large  in  comparison  with  the 
tract  through  which  it  varies,  then  it  comes  to  much  the 
same  whether  the  equi-probability  is  claimed  for  the  magni- 
tude itself  or  for  some  (ordinary)  function  thereof — the  square, 
or  square  root,  or  reciprocal,  etc.  For  example,  suppose  it  is 
sought  to  determine  with  precision  the  length  of  a  pendulum 
known  to  within  a  tenth  of  an  inch  to  be  about  a  yard  long. 
On  the  plausible  assumption  that  the  period  of  the  pendulum 
(the  time  occupied  by  an  oscillation)  is  d  priori  as  likely  to 
have  one  value  as  another  (in  the  immediate  neighbourhood 
of  that  period  which  corresponds  to  a  pendulum  a  yard  long), 
the  d  priori  probabilities  for  the  pendulum's  length  will  not 
be  distributed  with  perfect  equality.  Whereas  the  period  is 
proportionate  to  the  square-root  of  the  pendulum's  length,  it 
may  be  shown  that  the  probability  of  the  pendulum  having 
an  assigned  length  I,  meaning  thereby  a  length  between  I  and 
/  +  SI,  where  81  is  a  very  small  degree  of  length,  is  not  simply 
aSl  where  a  is  a  constant  (as  it  would  be  if  the  distribution 
were  perfectly  equal),  but  is  proportional  to  the  reciprocal  of 
the  square  root  of  I  =  say  6S\  -f-  ^/l,  where  b  is  a  constant. 
Now  by  hypothesis,  say,  I  lies  between  36  +  '1  inches  and 


264  F.  Y.  EDGEWOBTH: 

36  -  •!.  Whence  it  is  deducible  that  b  -r  \/l  differs  from 
b  -T-  6  by  less  than  '14  per  cent,  thereof.  Accordingly  the 
probability  of  I  being  the  true  value  is  very  nearly  SI  multi- 
plied by  a  constant  ;  the  d  priori  probabilities  of  the  different 
values  are  practically  equal. 

A  more  general  and  important  reason  for  the  neglect  of 
ci  priori  probabilities  in  dealing  with  observations  arises 
from  the  circumstance  that,  commonly  and  except  when  they 
are  very  unequal,  they  are  masked  and  overruled  by  the 
a  posteriori  evidence  which  the  observations  afford  if  ob- 
tained in  sufficient  numbers.  The  matter  is  well  put  by 
Mill  with  reference  to  the  case  which  we  have  distinguished 
as  special.  He  is  enquiring  whether  a  certain  event,  such 
as  a  succession  of  aces,  has  been  produced  by  accident,  or 
by  the  alternative  cause,  loading  of  the  dice.  "  We  may  be 
able  to  form  a  conjecture  as  to  the  antecedent  probability 
(of  loading)  .  .  .  but  it  would  clearly  be  impossible  to 
estimate  that  probability  with  anything  like  numerical  pre- 
cision. The  counter-probability,  however,  that  of  the  acci- 
dental origin  of  the  coincidence,  dwindling  so  soon  as  it  does 
at  each  new  trial,  the  stage  is  soon  reached  at  which  the 
chance  of  unfairness  in  the  die,  however  small  in  itself,  must 
be  greater  than  that  of  a  casual  coincidence  "  (Logic,  Book 
III.,  ch.  xviii.,  §  6).  Compare  Bertrand's  example  of  the 
inaccurate  roulette-table  (Ency.  Brit.,  loc.  tit.,  §  46).  The 
suppression  of  a  priori  probabilities,  as  we  may  call  the 
incident  explained  by  Mill,  was  almost  simultaneously  pointed 
out  by  Cournot  (Exposition  de  la  Theorie  des  Chances,  1843, 
§  95).  It  is  recognised  by  Mr.  Keynes  (p.  388).  It  is  ex- 
tended by  the  present  writer  to  the  general  case  of  magni- 
tudes other  than  ratios  (A  priori  Probabilities,  Philosophical 
Magazine,  1884,  vol.  xvii.,  p.  204 ;  cp.,  Journal  of  the  Eoyal 
Statistical  Society,  1908,  vol.  Ixxi.,  pp.  387,  392).  The  reason- 
ing does  not  require  the  d-  priori  values  of  the  tract  with  which 
we  are  concerned  to  be  very  nearly  equal ;  it  suffices  that 
they  should  not  be  very  unequal  (Ency.  Brit.,  loc.  cit.,  §§ 
8,  46).  Even  when  a  correction  is  prescribed  by  what  is 
known  about  a  priori  probability,  the  correction  is  in  general 
of  an  order  which  becomes  negligible  as  the  number  of 
observations  increases.  In  the  common  case  of  numerous 
observations  the  role  of  a  priori  probabilities  might  be  il- 
lustrated by  that  of  testimony  as  to  the  antecedents  of 
candidates  at  a  competitive  examination  for  appointments 
not  requiring  special  qualifications.  A  great  number  of 
candidates  might  be  practically  equal  as  to  nationality, 
absence  of  any  damaging  record,  and  other  antecedents. 


THE   PHILOSOPHY  OF  CHANCE.  265 

The  appointments  would  usually  be  given  to  those  who  did 
best  at  the  examination;  but  occasionally  the  antecedents 
might  affect  the  selection. 

The  assumptions  involved  in  the  usual  treatment  of  errors- 
of-observation  have  been  well  stated  by  Mr.  Keynes  (p.  191, 
vt  seq.}.  Indeed,  as  I  have  pointed  out  elsewhere  (Journ. 
Stat  Soc.,  1922,  p.  Ill),  he  has  made  a  notable  contribution 
to  the  mathematics  of  the  subject;  thereby  vindicating  a 
right  to  criticise  the  methods  of  the  calculus  which  is  hardly 
to  be  allowed  to  the  mere  logician.  But  I  think  he  does 
not  do  justice  to  a  very  important  application  of  the  doctrine 
of  errors,  the  method  of  sampling  as  now  practised,  by  Dr. 
Bowley  in  particular.  Here  the  ratios  or  other  measure- 
ments of  magnitude  which  the  sample  presents  are  treated 
as  observations  from  which  to  ascend  to  the  corresponding 
quantities  for  the  total  or  "universe"  from  which  the  sample 
is  taken  at  random.  The  danger  attending  statistical  infer- 
ence which  our  author  so  much  dreads  is  here  at  a  mini- 
mum. The  inductive  leap  from  the  known  to  the  un- 
known is  particularly  short ;  the  suppression  of  cu  priori 
probabilities  may  be  relied  on  if  the  sampling  is  thoroughly 
performed. 

It  is  not  irrelevant  to  remark  that  the  suppression  of 
d  priority  has  some  bearing  on  a  controversy  which  has  exer- 
cised great  minds,  concerning  the  so-called  Kule  of  Succession. 
The  unmeasured  ridicule  which  is  poured  upon  this  Rule  is 
deserved  only  when  it  is  applied  to  "  any  experience  however 
limited"  and  purports  to  prove  that  "  if  B  has  been  seen  to 
accompany  A  twice,  it  is  two  to  one  that  B  will  accompany 
A  on  A's  next  appearance  "  (p.  82.  Cp.t  p.  28,  note;  p.  377, 
et  seq.}.  But  when  the  relevant  a  priori  probabilities  (p.  376) 
are  overruled  by  the  number  of  the  observations,  as  may  be 
shown  by  the  reasoning  above  cited,  the  Eule  of  Succession 
is  by  no  means  so  absurd.  I  am  not  sure  but  that  it  may 
still  be  used  in  the  edifice  of  inductive  science,  not  indeed  as 
a  foundation,  but  as  one  of  the  cross-beams  in  that  compli- 
cated structure  (MiND,  p.  235).  If  so,  with  reference  to 
large  numbers  of  instances  as  supporting  induction  we  may 
still  say  of  the  Eule  in  question  with  Sir  John  Herschel :  "  It 
is  never  without  its  instruction  to  trace  this  sort  of  parallel 
between  mental  impressions  and  abstract  numerical  relations  " 
{Edinburgh  Beview,  1850,  vol.  xcii.,  p.  7;  Essays,  p,  376). 
I  am  not  much  moved  by  the  objection  that  in  this  view 
Probabilities  are  made  to  support  Induction,  while  Induction 
is  required  to  support  Probabilities.  Two  methods  by  their 
consilience  may  archwise  mutually  support  each  other.  At 


266  F.  Y.  EDGEWOBTH: 

least  the  consistency  of  first  principles  may  be  shown  by 
such  demonstrations  (cp.,  Ency.  Brit.,  loc.  cit.,  §  25). 

It  remains  to  examine  the  logical  basis  of  the  &  priori 
probabilities  which  we  have  been  considering.  I  have  main- 
tained that  the  ground  of  those  beliefs  is  a  very  wide  ex- 
perience, perhaps  of  the  unconscious  and  even  antenatal 
species,  which  some  prefer  to  call  intuitive  knowledge  (MiND, 
p.  229).  This  view  is,  I  hope,  not  inconsistent  with  Mr. 
Keynes*  description  of  the  judgments  derived  from  the 
Principle  of  Indifference  as  "direct"  (pp.  53,  65,  70,  316). 
Provided  that  the  cogency  of  the  evidence  is  granted,  I  do- 
not  much  mind  what  it  is  called.  On  the  issue  between 
intuitive  and  empirical  with  respect  to  the  propositions  in 
question,  I  am  disposed  to  repeat  what  Sir  John  Herschel 
has  said,  in  his  review  of  Whewell's  Philosophy,  with  respect, 
to  the  issue  in  other  cases:  "  it  seems  far  from  certain  that 
this  opposition  of  views  is  anything  more  than  apparent.  .  .  . 
On  either  view  of  the  subject  the  mind  of  man  is  represented 
as  in  harmony  with  universal  nature "  (Quarterly  Beview, 
184;  Essaijs,  p.  152).  The  followers  of  Mill  may  with  the 
less  scruple  admit  the  language  of  intuitionism  in  the  case 
before  us  since  it  is  not  claimed  for  a  priori  probabilities  that 
they  are  "necessary  "  in  a  sense  implying  that  they  dispense 
with,  and  are  not  liable  to  be  modified  by  the  addition  of, 
empirical  evidence.  It  is  agreed  that  a  priori  probability  is 
generally  negligible  in  comparison  with  the  evidence  of  re- 
peated observations — like  the  starlight  which  precedes  and 
fades  into  the  light  of  day. 

III.  THE  LOGIC  OF  STATISTICS. 

A  priori  probabilities  not  used  in  the  same  sense  as  in 
our  second  section  are  closely  connected  with  our  third 
section.  The  d  priori  propositions  now  relevant  are  prior 
not  to  all  positive  or  specific  experience,  but  only  to  that 
experience  which  forms  the  apparent  immediate  foundation 
of  an  induction.  The  inductions  to  be  considered  are  those 
which  establish  the  truth  of  those  quantified  generalisations 
which  are  presented  by  Statistics  and  by  Dr.  Venn  called 
probability  "  series  ".  There  seems  to  be  no  essential  differ- 
ence between  this  statistical  inference  and  the  induction 
which  establishes  ordinary  universal  generalisations  (cp., 
Keynes,  ch.  xxvii.  and  p.  391).  My  only  contribution  to  this 
logic  is  to  insist,  with  Mill  and  others,  on  the  part  played 
in  all  our  inductions  by  pre-existing  knowledge  (cp.,  Mill, 
Logic,  Book  III.,  ch.  iii.,  §  3;  ch.  iv.,  §§  2,  3).  This  sub- 


THE   PHILOSOPHY  OF   CHANCE.  267 

stratum  may  consist  of  the  so-called  direct  or  intuitive- 
generalisations  considered  in  our  second  section ;  or  of  gen- 
eralisations which  are  the  outcome  of  experience  in  the 
ordinary  sense.  Both  kinds  of  pre-existent  knowledge  were 
noticed  in  MIND,  1884 ;  and  more  explicitly  with  reference 
to  statistical  inference  in  a  paper  written  a  year  later.  Ar> 
"  abscission  of  certain  antecedents  as  immaterial  is  constantly 
going  on  in  inductive  logic  by  ...  an  almost  unconscious  pro- 
cess. It  is  presupposed  in  every  act  of  the  Method  of  Differ- 
ence. The  chemist  rejects  historical  events  as  immaterial ; 
the  historian  the  conjuncture  of  the  stars.  There  is  in 
each  case  a  vast  substructure  of  previous  knowledge  of  the- 
connexion  between  things;  not  very  prominent  perhaps  in 
treatises  on  logic,  yet  constituting  the  foundations  of  wisdom  " 
(Journal  of  the  Royal  Statistical  Society,  December,  1885). 
So  Dr.  Marshall  in  an  address  on  the  "  Graphical  Method  of 
Statistics  "  (in  the  Jubilee  number  of  the  same  Journal,  1885) 
directs  us  to  estimate  the  nature  of  the  dependence  of  an 
observed  event  A  on  each  of  the  possible  causes  B,  C,  D  .  .  . ; 
"  our  reason  making  use  of  that  abstract  and  essence  of  past 
experience  which  is  on  the  one  side  science  and  on  the  other 
practical  instinct". 

The  view  that  pre-existing  knowledge  plays  a  great  part 
in  induction  is  convincingly  reaffirmed  by  Mr.  Keynes.  It 
is  well  illustrated  by  the  supposed  irrationality  of  primitive- 
peoples  ;  really  due  to  their  want  of  previous  relevant  know- 
ledge. Thus  "it  is  a  curious  superstition"  of  a  tribe  in 
Borneo,  as  described  by  a  recent  pioneer,  "  to  attribute  any- 
thing that  happens  to  them  to  something  novel  which  has 
arrived  in  their  country  " ;  for  instance  intensely  hot  weather 
to  the  pioneer's  arrival.  "  What  is  this  curious  superstition 
but  the  Method  of  Difference,"  pertinently  asks  Mr.  Keynes. 

Behind  the  inductive  methods  are  the  more  essential  prin- 
ciples of  analogy  or  likeness,  pure  induction  or  repetition. 
Pure  induction  avails  not  without  some  finite  initial  proba- 
bility in  favour  of  the  generalisation,  obtained  from  some- 
other  source  than  the  instances  examined  (pp.  238,  295,  302: 
et  passim).  A  "  finite  probability,"  it  should  be  explained,, 
is  "  one  which  exceeds  some  numerical  probability  the  ratio 
of  which  to  certainty  can  be  expressed  by  a  finite  number" 
(p.  237).  It  would  come  to  the  same,  as  I  understand,  to 
take  as  the  condition  that  an  indefinitely  great  a  priori  im- 
probability does  not  attach  to  the  generalisation  which  it  is 
sought  to  prove.  Or  perhaps  the  latter  statement  is  not 
equally  stringent.  For  Mr.  Keynes  appears  to  rule  out  as- 
not  satisfying  his  condition  a  generalisation  connecting  the 


268  F.  Y.  EDGEWOBTH: 

weights  of  babies  with  their  Christian  names  (p.  426).  Yet 
no  extreme  improbability  attaches  to  that  generalisation. 
Certain  Christian  names  popular  among  families  of  a  par- 
ticular race  or  sect  might  predominate  among  particular 
sections  of  the  population.  The  inherited  qualities  of  the 
race,  or  the  habits  enjoined  by  the  faith,  might  be  attended 
with  peculiarities  in  vital  statistics  generally  and  in  particular 
as  to  the  weight  of  babies.  So  easy  an  explanation  might 
not  always  be  forthcoming.  But,  as  in  the  case  of  conjuring 
tricks  which  we  cannot  explain,  there  may  be  a  general  a 
priori  probability  that  there  is  an  intelligible  explanation. 
Of  course  it  would  not  be  contended  that  the  observed  uni- 
formity would  hold  good  outside  the  environment  within 
which  it  was  observed  ;  it  would  not  be  true  in  every  country 
that  certain  Christian  names  are  attended  with  certain 
peculiarities  of  infant  life.  Parents  could  not  even  in  the 
observed  country  secure  that  their  children  should  be  fat 
and  well-liking  by  giving  them  names  correlated  with  weight 
above  the  average.  I  concede  to  Mr.  Keynes  that  the  mathe- 
matical method  of  correlation  as  usually  understood  and 
practised  does  not  avail  to  prove  more  than  empirical  general- 
isations. 

But  I  think  that  he  has  somewhat  underrated  the  power 
of  the  method  to  establish  such  generalisations.  He  puts  a 
case  which  does  not  bring  into  action  that  grip  of  quantita- 
tive data  which  is  characteristic  of  the  mathematical  method. 
Let  us  vary  his  illustration  by  imagining  that  there  is 
observed  a  connexion  between  the  number  of  ounces  that  an 
infant  weighs  and  the  number  of  letters  in  its  name  or  names, 
on  the  supposition  that  the  average  infant  has  several  names. 
Say  the  average  number  of  letters  is  considerable,  well  above 
a  dozen ;  and  construct  a  table  showing  the  frequency  with 
which  each  number  of  letters  in  the  full  name  is  associated 
with  each  number  of  ounces  in  the  weight  of  an  infant.  Sup- 
pose that  this  construction  fulfils  accurately  the  conditions  of 
a  normal  frequency -surf ace  with  correlation-coefficient  large 
and  positive  (cp.,  Yule,  Theory  of  Statistics,  ch.  ix.).  Let 
the  number  of  observations  be  large ;  and  let  the  grouping 
pass  triumphantly  the  criteria  which  may  be  applied  to  test 
whether  it  conforms  to  a  normal  error-surface.  The  case 
would  thus  present  a  complex  and  close  resemblance  to  the 
more  perfect  exemplifications  of  normal  correlation  which 
are  exhibited  in  recent  treatises  on  Statistics.  It  may  be 
expected  therefore  that  our  case  will  also  resemble  those  ex- 
amples in  a  certain  stability,  such  that  if  you  examine  some 
fresh  instances — in  addition  to  the  mass  of  observations 


THE   PHILOSOPHY  OF   CHANCE.  269 

which  evidenced  normal  correlation — the  fresh  batch  would 
present  much  the  same  connexion  between  the  attributes 
(in  the  case  before  us  length  of  name  and  number  of  ounces) 
as  was  observed  in  the  original  large  group.  The  inference, 
I  think,  would  come  under  one  of  Mr.  Keynes'  general 
canons :  that  the  more  comprehensive  the  characteristics  in 
which  the  instances  are  similar  the  stronger  is  the  proba- 
bility of  the  generalisation  we  seek  to  establish  (p.  219). 

Mr.  Keynes  has  carried  much  further  his  enquiry  concern- 
ing the  nature  and  functions  of  analogy  and  induction.  But 
I  do  not  propose  to  follow  him  into  this  obscure  region; 
which  lies  somewhat  apart  from  the  topics  which  are  here 
reconsidered.  But  there  is  one  tenet  of  the  higher  Logic 
which  cannot  be  passed  over  by  a  writer  on  Chance.  As 
the  "peering  eye  of  philosophy"  is  strained  to  explore  the 
origins  of  knowledge  there  is  dimly  discerned  a  first  prin- 
ciple which  is  of  momentous  interest  to  the  student  of  Prob- 
abilities :  "  The  character  of  material  laws  on  which  scientists, 
appear  commonly  to  act,  seems  to  me  much  less  simple  than 
the  bare  principle  of  Uniformity  (as  to  whi9h  see  pp.  226, 
255,  263).  They  appear  to  assume  something  much  more 
like  what  mathematicians  call  the  principle  of  the  super- 
position of  small  effects,  or,  as  I  prefer  to  call  it,  in  this  con- 
nexion, the  atomic  character  of  natural  law.  The  system  of 
the  material  universe  must  consist,  if  this  kind  of  assumption 
is  warranted,  of  bodies  which  we  may  term  (without  any 
implication  as  to  their  size  being  conveyed  thereby)  legal 
atoms,  such  that  each  of  them  exercises  its  own  separate 
independent  and  invariable  effect,  a  change  of  the  total  state- 
being  compounded  of  a  number  of  separate  changes  each  of 
which  is  due  to  a  separate  portion  of  the  preceding  state  " 
(p.  249). 

Whatever  the  claims  of  this  principle  to  be  characteristic 
of  the  universe,  it  is  at  least  congruous  with  the  nature  of 
things  in  so  far  as  it  postulates  conditions  required  by,  or  at 
least  conducive  to,  the  realisation  of  a  law  which  is  or  tends, 
to  be  approximately  realised  throughout  wide  fields  of  ex- 
istence, the  "normal  law  of  error".  I  so  designate  that 
grouping  of  statistics  about  their  average,  that  relation  be- 
tween the  extent  of  a  deviation  and  its  frequency,  which 
Galton  and  many  modern  statisticians  have  made  familiar. 
It  seems  best  to  restrict  the  term  "  law  "  in  this  connexion 
to  the  conception  of  that  relation,  the  form  of  the  curve  (or,, 
in  more  complicated  cases,  surface)  which  represents  the 
grouping ;  as  distinguished  from  the  proposition  which  may 
be  called  the  "  theory  "  of  error,  that,  given  certain  conditions, 


^70  F.  Y.  EDGEWOKTH: 

the  law  will  be  realised.  To  which  perhaps  should  be 
-added  the  proposition  (without  which  the  theory  would  have 
no  practical  importance)  that  the  conditions  are  fairly  often 
fulfilled  in  rerum  naturd,  sufficiently  well  for  the  (approxi- 
mate) realisation  of  the  normal  law  of  error.  The  theory  is 
to  be  distinguished  from  the  doctrine,  the  false  doctrine,  that 
generally,  wherever  there  is  a  curve  with  single  apex  repre- 
senting a  group  of  statistics — one  axis  denoting  size,  the 
other  axis  frequency — that  curve  must  be  of  the  "  normal  " 
species.  The  doctrine  has  been  nicknamed  "  Quetelismus," 
on  the  ground  that  Quetelet  exaggerated  the  prevalence  of 
the  normal  law. 

The  conditions  proper  to  the  fulfilment  of  the  normal  law 
by  a  variable  magnitude  are  two-fold  :  that  it  should  depend 
upon  a  number  of  causes,  and  that  those  causes  should  be 
independent  of  each  other.  Or  rather,  as  the  term  "  inde- 
pendent "  is  here  to  be  taken  in  each  of  two  senses,  there  are 
three  conditions  :  (1)  The  quantity  conforming  to  the  normal 
law  should  be  a  compound,  composed  of  numerous  constituent 
•elements ;  (2)  each  element  should  fluctuate  independently 
(in  the  sense  proper  to  Probabilities)  of  the  others ;  (3)  the 
•composition  should  be  simple,  the  compound  being  a  sum 
of  the  elements  (or  a  sum  of  components  each  of  which  de- 
pends on — is  a  function  of — a  single  element).  The  last 
two  conditions  are  given  by  Mr.  Keynes'  axioms.  In  criti- 
cising the  statistical  side  of  his  treatise  (in  the  Statistical 
Society's  Journal,  1922)  I  have  complained  that  he  has  not 
•adequately  recognised  the  leading  law  of  Statistics,  the. 
theory  of  error.  I  have  now  to  add  that  he  makes  amends 
for  that  omission  by  showing  the  prevalence  of  the  condi- 
tions which  underlie  that  theory. 

The  significance  of  the  conditions  may  be  exhibited  by 
considering  their  more  or  less  perfect  fulfilment  in  different 
.spheres.  With  respect  to  errors-of-observation,  errors 
proper  as  they  may  be  called  (as  distinguished  from  "  errors  " 
used  generically  for  deviations  from  an  average),  I  quote 
from  a  high  authority  on  Probabilities,  Morgan  Crofton 
(author  of  the  article  on  the  Theory  of  Probability  in  the 
ninth  edition  of  the  Encyclopedia  Britannica).  He  is  main- 
taining the  hypothesis  (consonant  with  our  theory)  that 
'"  errors  (of  observation)  in  rerum  naturd  result  from  the 
superposition  of  a  large  number  of  minuter  errors  arising 
from  a  number  of  independent  sources  ".  He  proceeds  :  "  In 
coarse  and  rude  observations  the  errors  proceed  from  a  very 
.few  principal  causes,  and  in  this  case,  consequently,  our 
hypothesis  will  probably  represent  the  facts  only  imperfectly, 


THE   PHILOSOPHY  OF   CHANCE.  271 

and  the  frequency  of  the  errors  will  only  approximate  roughly 
and  vaguely  to  the  law  which  follows  from  it  "  [referring  to 
the  normal  law  of  error].  ..."  When  these  few  capital 
occasions  of  error  were  removed  "...  astronomers  "  found 
that  not  three  or  four,  but  a  great  number  of  minor  sources 
of  error,  of  nearly  co-ordinate  importance,  began  to  reveal 
themselves  .  .  .  errors  of  their  adjustments ;  errors  (techni- 
cally so  called)  of  observation  [?  due  to  the  imperfection  of 
the  observer's  senses] ;  errors  from  change  of  temperature,  of 
weather,  from  slight  irregular  motions  and  vibrations ;  in 
short,  the  thousand  minute  disturbing  influences  with  which 
modern  astronomers  are  familiar."  But  "it  is  not  enough 
for  us  to  show  that  each  error  in  practice  is  compounded 
of  a  large  number  of  smaller  errors  ;  we  must  also  show  that 
they  are  independent,  at  least  for  the  most  part".  Admitting 
that  some  of  the  errors  may  be  interdependent  he  yet  sums 
up  "we  may  at  least  safely  conclude  that  the  hypothesis  in 
question  is  not  a  mere  arbitrary  assumption,  but  a  reasonable 
and  probable  account  of  what  does  in  fact  take  place  "  (Trans- 
actions of  the  Royal  Society,  1870,  pp.  175-177).  This  con- 
clusion is  in  accordance  with  the  "  atomic  character  of  natural 
law"  postulated  by  Mr.  Keynes.  It  is  assumed  not  that 
there  is  never  correlation  between  the  phenomena,  but  that 
"for  the  most  part,"  or  at  least  in  good  part,  independence 
prevails.  A  similar  explanation  is  available  in  a  neighbour- 
ing department  within  which  the  normal  law  of  error  may 
be  expected  and  is  found — the  distribution  of  shot  marks  on 
a  target. ,  The  varying  causes  affecting  the  aim  are  like  to 
those  enumerated  by  Crofton  ;  and  there  are  additional  in- 
dependent causes  affecting  the  flight  of  the  bullet  however 
well  aimed,  inequalities  of  charge,  tremors  of  the  air  and  so 
forth.  If  the  barrel  of  a  rifle  is  fixed  firmly,  and  successive 
shots  are  fired  so  as  to  hit  a  target  at  some  distance,  it  is 
found  that  the  bullet-marks  are  dispersed  ;  owing  to  the  opera- 
tion of  the  latter  class  of  causes  only.  It  is  presumable  that 
a  like  plurality  of  independent  causes  operates  in  a  third 
class  of  instances,  the  organs  and  attributes  of  natural  species, 
for  instance  the  height  of  adult  males  in  a  homogeneous 
population,  or  other  measurements  as  tabulated  by  a  Galton 
or  Pearson.  The  causation  by  which  the  magnitudes  of  in- 
herited attributes  are  distributed  may  perhaps  be  illustrated 
by  a  sort  of  heredity  which  occurs  in  a  fourth  sphere  favour- 
able to  the  genesis  of  the  law-of-error,  the  movement  of 
molecules  in  a  free  gas.  The  velocity  of  a  molecule  at  any 
time  maybe  regarded  as  the  offspring  of  two  parent  velo- 
cities, namely  the  velocity  of  the  molecule  itself  before  its 


272  F.  Y.  EDGEWOETH: 

latest  collision  with  another,  and  the  velocity  of  that  other 
before  the  collision.  The  two  parents  were  likewise  sprung 
each  from  two  parents ;  and  so  on.  The  velocities  of  the 
system  at  any  moment  may  be  regarded  as  simply  com- 
pounded of  numerous  elements  fluctuating  independently 
(cp.,  "Applications  of  Probability  to  the  Movement  of  Gas 
Molecules,"  Philosophical  Magazine,  Sept.  1920 ;  and 
"  Molecular  Statistics,"  Journal  of  the  Eoyal  Statistical 
Society,  Jan.  1921).  It  is  no  wonder  therefore  that  the  law- 
of-error  should  be  found  in  great  perfection  in  a  medley  of 
molecules ;  visible  to  the  eye  of  reason,  and  almost  to  the 
natural  eye  through  their  action  upon  visible  granules 
("  Brownian  "  movements). 

This  theory  deserves  the  attention  of  philosophers  as 
affording  a  particularly  unequivocal  and  striking  instance  of 
positive  knowledge  that  seems  to  be  obtained  d  priori  or  by 
intuition.  It  seems  as  if  "it  might  have  been  certainly 
known  to  be  true  independent  of  experience  "  ;  what  Whewell 
claims  for  the  Newtonian  first  law  of  motion.  Of  course 
Whewell  did  not  mean  that  we  obtain  the  particulars  of  any 
instance  d  priori.  Through  sensation,  or  from  some  other 
empirical  source,  we  ascertain  the  minor  premiss  that  there 
is  no  obstacle  impeding  the  motion  of  a  certain  body ;  and 
then  by  the  first  law  of  motion  given  d  priori  we  conclude 
that  the  body  will  go  on  moving  at  a  constant  rate.  The 
theory  is  not  falsified  because  in  everyday  life  we  do  not 
often  meet  with  a  vacuum.  So  in  the  theory  now  under 
consideration  what  is  supposed  to  be  given  d  priori  is  not 
the  fact  that  a  certain  magnitude  is  a  compound  of  numerous 
constituent  elements,  but  that,  if  it  is  a  compound,  the  com- 
ponents will  be  independent  of  each  other  "  for  the  most 
part  "  as  Crofton  has  it,  or  at  least  adequately  for  the  genesis- 
of  the  law  of  error  when  the  number  of  components  is  con- 
siderable. The  fact  that  the  normal  law  of  error  is  not  very 
commonly  realised  in  great  perfection  is  not  fatal  to  the 
theory  of  error  as  here  defined,  but  only  to  the  false  doctrine 
of  "  Quetelismus ".  Where  only  "  a  very  few  principal 
causes,"  in  Morgan  Crof ton's  phrase,  are  present,  there,  as 
he  admits,  "  our  hypothesis  will  probably  represent  the  facts 
but  imperfectly  ". 

We  have  thus  a  new  instance  of  d  priori  evidence  claimed 
for  propositions  outside  pure  mathematics  and  metaphysics. 
The  new  instance  is  more  striking  and  paradoxical  than  the 
one  presented  by  the  Principle  of  Sufficient  Keason.  For 
no  one  can  doubt  but  that  the  propositions  now  before  us — 
the  fact  for  instance  that  the  heights  of  an  adult  male  popu- 


THE  PHILOSOPHY   OF   CHANCE.  273 

lation  conform  to  a  certain  simple  formula — are  matters  of 
fact  rather  than  relations  of  ideas — to  use  the  antithesis 
strongly  marked  by  Hume  when  denning  the  province  of 
experience  (Concerning  human  intellect :  Sceptical  doubts, 
pars.  1  and  2  et  passim).  That  positive  knowledge  should 
be  deducible  from  axioms  of  a  seemingly  metaphysical  char- 
acter is  certainly  most  remarkable.  We  seem  to  be  revert- 
ing from  modern  physics  to  the  natural  philosophy  of  the 
ancient  Greeks.  But  the  anomaly  and  anachronism  disappear 
if  the  second  instance,  as  well  as  the  first  (MiND,  loc.  cit, 
p.  229),  is  explained  as  a  case  of  induction,  induction  of  the 
kind  which  Mill  regards  as  adequate  to  support  the  proposi- 
tions claimed  by  Whewell  as  a  priori  :  "experimental  proof 
crowds  in  upon  us  in  such  endless  profusion,  and  without 
one  instance  in  which  there  can  be  even  a  suspicion  of  an 
exception  to  the  rule  "  (Logic,  Book  II.,  ch.  vi.,  §  4). 

IV.  APPLICATION  OF  PROBABILITIES  TO  CONDUCT. 

The  use  of  "mathematical  expectation"  as  a  guide  to 
conduct  is  the  principal  application  which  we  have  to  consider. 
"  In  order  to  obtain  a  measure  of  what  ought  to  be  our  pre- 
ference in  regard  to  various  alternative  courses  of  action  we 
must  sum  for  each  course  of  action  a  series  of  terms  made 
up  of  the  amounts  of  good  which  may  attach  to  each  of  its 
possible  consequences,  each  multiplied  by  its  appropriate 
probability "  (p.  311).  Against  this  maxim  Mr.  Keynes 
brings  three  objections  of  which  the  first  two  appear  not 
very  formidable. 

First,  there  is  renewed  with  respect  to  the  product  of 
probability  and  prospective  good  a  difficulty  which  we  have 
already  encountered — and,  I  trust,  overcome — the  difficulty 
ascribed  to  the  want  of  numerical  precision.  "  Normal 
ethical  theory  at  the  present  day,  if  there  can  be  said  to  be 
any  such,  makes  two  assumptions :  first,  that  degrees  of 
goodness  are  numerically  measurable  and  arithmetically 
additive,  and  second,  that  degrees  of  probability  also  are 
numerically  measurable  "  (p.  311).  There  seems  to  be  here 
set  up,  in  order  to  be  knocked  down,  a  somewhat  exaggerated 
claim  on  behalf  of  utilitarian  ethics.  With  respect  to  the 
second  factor  of  Expectation,  viz.,  Probability,  we  need  not 
postulate  greater  precision  than  we  have  already  claimed 
on  the  model  of  physical  mensuration  as  interpreted  by  Profs. 
Eddington  and  Love.  The  authority  of  Poincare  may  be 
quoted  for  treating  satisfaction  (subjective  good)  in  the  same 
spirit.  In  a  letter  to  Walras  (the  mathematical  economist) 

18 


274  F.  Y.  EDGEWORTH: 

the  great  mathematician  rules :  "  Satisfaction  then  is  a 
magnitude,  but  not  a  measurable  magnitude  ".  But  it  is  not 
"  par  cela  seul  exclue  de  toute  speculation  mathematique  " 
(see  Economic  Journal,  1915,  p.  57,  for  reference  and  fuller 
quotation).  It  deserves,  indeed,  to  be  considered  whether, 
when  we  are  dealing  with  this  subjective  quantity,  the  use 
of  a  unit  such  as  I 'have  proposed  (Mathematical  Psychics, 
Part  II.),  namely  the  "  just  perceivable  increment "  (of 
pleasurable  feeling),  does  not  come  to  much  the  same  as  the 
use  of  subdivisions  analogous  to  those  employed  by  Prof. 
Eddington  with  respect  to  physical  quantity.  "  The  sub- 
division," he  writes,  "must  be  continued  until  the  meshes 
are  so  small  that  all  points  in  one  mesh  can  be  considered 
identical  within  the  limits  of  experimental  detection  "  (Space, 
Time  and  Gravitation,  p.  77).  But  without  insisting  on  these 
refinements,  is  it  not  evident  that  without  having  more 
exact  relations  than  those  of  "more"  and  "less"  we  can 
infer  that  the  product  of  a  and  b,  ab,  is  greater  than  a/3  if  it 
is  given  that  a>a,  b>/3  ?  We  can  make  this  inference  even 
without  the  second  datum,  if  it  is  known  that  a  is  very  much 
greater  than  a,  while  b  is  known  not  to  be  much  greater  than 
/3.  As  before  about  magnitudes  of  one  dimension,  may  there 
not  be  clear  perceptions  of  greater  and  less  without  numerical 
precision  ?  To  go  back  to  the  heroic  age,  if  Priam  saw  that 
Ajax  was  taller  and  broader  than  the  other  Greeks,  would  he 
not  perceive  that  the  area  subtended  by  the  figure  of  Ajax 
was  greater  than  that  of  the  others  ?  Might  he  not  have 
observed  the  same  of  Ulysses  compared  with  Agamemnon,  if 
the  former,  though  (slightly)  shorter,  had  been  (very  much) 
broader  than  the  latter  :- — 


aev  K.€<ba\r)v  'A"yafJL€fJ.vovos  'ArpetSao, 

(Iliad  III.,  193-4.) 


A  second  difficulty  is  raised  in  connexion  with  what  is 
termed  the  "Weight"  of  a  probability.  "Weight"  is  de- 
fined by  the  statement  that  "  an  accession  of  new  evidence 
increases  the  weight  of  an  argument  "  (ch.  vi.).  How  should 
we  be  influenced  in  our  choice  of  a  course  of  action  by 
the  "  weight "  of  that  probability  which  is  a  factor  of  the 
Expectation  ?  The  question  may  be  answered  in  terms  of 
the  analogy  presented  by  the  theory  of  errors-of-observation. 
Suppose  that  there  are  given  a  finite  number  of  observations, 
which  it  is  required  to  combine  so  as  to  obtain  the  best  pos- 
sible value  for  the  object  under  measurement.  It  is  not 
necessary  with  our  author  to  fix  attention  on  the  most  pro- 
bable value,  and  the  probable  error  as  measured  therefrom 


THE   PHILOSOPHY  OF   CHANCE.  275 

(p.  74).  It  is  better,  as  I  have  elsewhere  pointed  out,  with 
Laplace  to  seek,  not  that  combination  of  the  given  observa- 
tions which  is  most  probably  (most  frequently  in  the  long 
run  of  similar  data)  right,  but  the  one  which,  minimising  the 
detriment  incident  to  the  use  of  fallible  observations,  maxi- 
mises the  Expectation  of  useful  results.  In  short  there  is 
applied  to  the  treatment  of  observations  the  principle  which 
should  govern  all  conduct  considered  as  part  of  a  "series,"  a 
rule  to  be  universally  adopted.  The  significance  of  Laplace's 
conception  appears  in  Simon  Newcomb's  estimates  of  the 
"  Good  "  and  "  Evil  "  pertaining  to  astronomical  observations 
{American  Journal  of  Mathematics,  vol.  viii.,  no.  4).  As 
a  first-rate  mathematical  economist  the  great  astronomer  was 
prepared  to  handle  quantities  less  definite  and  measureable 
than  the  objective  magnitudes  with  which  the  physicist  has 
usually  to  deal.  In  the  common  case  of  numerous  observa- 
tions mathematical  theory  affords  an  index  of  the  detriment. 
In  general  that  detriment  increases  with  the  increase,  and 
decreases  with  the  decrease,  of  the  "  spread  "  or  "  scatter  " 
of  the  observations  as  defined  by  the  mean  square  of  their 
deviation  from  the  true  point.  Thus  in  the  example  given 
in  our  Section  II.  (if  OX  =  x)  the  mean  square  of  deviation  is 

{(x  -  xtf  +  (x  -  z2)2  +    .  .  .    +  (x  -  xnY}  ~  n. 

Now  let  us  suppose  that  the  mean  square  pertaining  to 
{observations  made  with)  a  particular  instrument  has  been 
ascertained  from  a  long  series  of  trials  prior  to  the  measure- 
ment for  which  we  have  to  prescribe.  The  longer  the  series 
(ceteris  paribus\  the  more  accurate  will  be  the  determination 
of  the  mean  square  of  error.  Let  us  take  the  reciprocal  of 
the  mean  square  as  index  of  the  worth  of  a  measurement 
with  that  instrument  (what  is  called  "  weight"  by  Lap- 
lace and  his  followers) ;  and  let  us  say  that  the  "evidential 
weight"  (Keynes,  ch.  vi.)  of  "worth"  is  greater  the  more 
extensive  the  previous  experience  on  which  it  is  based.  Then 
of  two  instruments  or  methods  of  measurement  for  which 
the  ostensible  worth  is  the  same  that  one  is  to  be  preferred 
for  which  the  evidential  weight  is  greater.  But,  if  there  is  a 
difference  in  worth  as  well  as  in  evidential  weight,  it  is  con- 
ceivable that  a  measurement  of  somewhat  less  worth  but 
considerably  greater  evidential  weight  than  another  might  be 
preferable  to  that  other/  I  leave  it  to  the  reader  to  construct 
an  analogue  of  this  mathematical  theory  applicable  to  or- 
dinary life. 

It  will  be  found,  I  think,  that  the  second  objection  only 
gives  us  pause  when  it  is  associated  with  the  third,  that 


276  F.  Y.  EDGEWOETH: 

which  arises  when  an  action  is  regarded  as  solitary,  not 
forming  part  of  a  long  run  or  "series".  To  exhibit  this 
difficulty  is,  I  think,  the  main  purport  of  the  Petersburg 
problem ;  though  not  the  only  lesson  which  it  conveys.  The 
problem  is  thus  stated  by  Mr.  Keynes :  "  Peter  engages  to 
pay  Paul  one  shilling  if  a  head  appears  at  the  first  toss  of  a 
coin,  two  shillings  if  it  does  not  appear  until  the  second,  and 
in  general  2r~1  shillings  if  no  head  appears  until  the  rth 
toss.  What  is  the  value  of  Paul's  expectation?"  (p.  316). 
The  mathematical  answer  is :  if  the  number  of  tosses  is  not 
in  any  case  to  exceed  n  in  all,  %n  shillings ;  and  if  this 
restriction  is  removed,  an  infinite  sum.  Mr.  Keynes  appears 
to  great  advantage  in  the  discussion  of  this  problem ;  his 
logical  acumen  enhanced  by  his  unusually  wide  acquaintance 
with  the  foreign  literature  of  Probabilities.  I  take  as  a  text 
for  some  general  reflexions  his  summary  of  the  different 
reasons  which  have  been  assigned  for  the  fact  that  (n  being 
large)  no  sensible  person  would  give  for  Paul's  chances 
anything  like  the  mathematical  expectation.  "  Each  of  the 
above  solutions  probably  contains  a  great  part  of  the  psycho- 
logical explanation.  We  are  unwilling  to  be  Paul  partly 
because  we  do  not  believe  Peter  will  pay  us  if  we  have  good 
fortune  in  the  tossing,  partly  because  we  do  not  know  what 
we  should  do  with  so  much  money  or  sand  or  hydrogen  if  we 
won  it,  partly  because  we  do  not  believe  we  ever  should  win 
it.  and  partly  because  we  do  not  think  it  would  be  a  rational 
act  to  risk  an  infinite  sum  or  even  a  very  large  sum  for  an 
infinitely  larger  one  whose  attainment  is  infinitely  unlikely  '" 
(p.  319). 

I  take  these  points  in  the  order  of  the  summary. 

We  do  not  believe  that  Peter  will  pay  us  a  sum  which 
may  be  vastly  in  excess  of  his  means.  This  objection  is  met 
by  the  ingenious  suggestion  which  Mr.  Keynes  cites  from  a 
foreign  authority  that  the  stakes  should  be  (not  shillings  or 
francs,  but)  grains  of  sand  or  molecules  of  hydrogen  (p.  317). 

We  should  not  know  what  to  do  with  so  much  money  or 
sand,  we  might  have  a  surfeit  of  winnings,  by  reason  of  the 
law  of  diminishing  utility ;  which  was,  I  believe,  first  formu- 
lated in  connexion  with  the  Petersburg  problem.  Keferring 
to  the  law  that  the  value  of  a  sum  of  money  to  a  man  varies 
with  the  amount  he  already  possesses,  Mr.  Keynes  asks 
"  Does  the  value  of  an  amount  of  goodness  also  vary  in  this 
way?  May  it  not  be  true  that  the  addition  of  a  given 
good  to  a  man  who  already  enjoys  much  good  is  less  good 
than  its  bestowal  on  a  man  who  has  little  ?  "  (p.  320).  This 
recalls  the  precept  of  the  late  Cohen  Stuart  for  dis- 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  CHANCE.  277 

tributing  the  burden  of  taxation ;  that  each  taxpayer  should 
forgo,  not  an  equal  amount  of  satisfaction,  but,  an  equal 
percentage  of  the  total  satisfaction  which  he  derives  from  his 
income  (see  Economic  Journal,  1897,  p.  559  and  context). 
Cohen  Stuart's  criterion  has  been  adopted  by  some  sensible 
persons,  notably  Prof.  Seligman,  and  the  late  Leonard 
Courtney. 

We  do  not  believe  that  our  winnings  will  ever  be  immense, 
if  we  hold  with  D'Alembert  and  Dr.  Marbe  (pp.  317,  365) 
that  long  runs  are  not  only  very  improbable,  but  do  not 
occur  at  all.  Experiment  gives  no  colour  of  verification  to 
this  statement.  Yet  a  priori  on  grounds  of  general  ex- 
perience I  am  prepared  to  find  that  some  sort  of  periodicity 
in  the  manner  of  making  the  experiments,  the  way  of  pro- 
jecting the  coin,  for  instance,  would  result  in  a  certain 
correlation  between  the  observations;  and  accordingly  that 
the  convergence  of  the  average,  and  likewise  the  frequency 
of  runs,  would  not  be  exactly  what  the  regulation  formula 
enounces  (in  terms  of  n  the  total  number  of  tosses).  This 
consideration  would  not  indeed  rule  out  indefinitely  long 
runs.  Still,  as  Dr.  Venn  observes  in  this  connexion  (op.  cit., 

E.  83),  "  there  are  so  many  instances  in  nature  of  proposed 
LWS  which  hold  within  narrow  limits  but  get  egregiously 
astray  when  we  attempt  to  push  them  to  great  lengths,  that 
we  must  give  at  best  but  a  qualified  assent  to  the  formula  ". 
Accordingly  I  am  not  disposed  with  Mr.  Keynes  to  dismiss 
as  trivial  the  observations  obtained  by  recording  the  results 
of  trials  made  with  instruments  of  chance  (p.  366).  This 
experience  may  satisfy  not  merely  "a  certain  idle  curiosity," 
but  also  a  certain  scientific  interest.  One  would  like  to 
know,  for  instance,  the  explanation  of  the  difference  between 
the  results  of  Prof.  Pearson's  and  Dr.  Marbe's  investigations. 
The  former,  on  examining  33,000  coups  at  the  roulette  table 
of  Monte  Carlo,  found  the  frequency  of  long  runs  greatly 
in  excess  of  the  regulation  proportion  ;  the  latter,  on  ex- 
amining 80,000  coups,  found  that  the  long  runs  were  greatly 
in  defect  (p.  365). 

The  lesson  which  the  Petersburg  problem  is  specially 
adapted  to  convey  is  connected  with  the  third  and  most 
serious  of  the  objections  to  the  use  of  mathematical  expect- 
ation as  the  guide  of  action.  It  is  seen  to  be  no  longer  a 
safe  guide  in  the  case  of  transactions  which  cannot  be  re- 
garded as  forming  part  of  a  "series"  in  Dr.  Venn's  sense. 
How  far  the  proposed  case  is  from  fulfilling  that  condition 
will  appear  if  we  consider  what  changes  of  statement  would 
be  required  in  order  to  render  the  problem  amenable  to  the 


278  R  Y.  EDGEWORTH: 

calculus  of  probabilities.  We  should  suppose  that  the  offer 
made  to  Paul  is  renewed  from  time  to  time ;  say  repeated 
every  day  throughout  a  whole  year.  Also  the  amount  that 
he  can  possibly  win  on  any  one  day  should  be  finite  and 
moderate.  Say,  Peter  will  give  the  same  as  before  in  case 
Head  turns  up  at  the  first,  second,  third,  or  fourth  toss ;  but 
that  if  it  turns  up  after  the  fourth  toss,  however  long  after — 
however  long  the  run  of  Tails — Peter  will  still  give  no  more 
than  he  will  give  if  Head  turns  up  at  the  fourth  toss,  that 
is,  8s.  Then  Paul's  Expectation  is  shown  by  the  following 
scheme : — 

Winnings    ...     1         2         4         8 
Probability  .     -£         J        £        £ 

Multiplying  each  figure  on  the  upper  line  by  the  correspond- 
ing figure  on  the  lower  line,  and  adding  the  products,  we 
obtain  for  the  amount  which  Paul  may  expect  to  win  in  the 
course  of  the  year  2'5  x  365  =  912'5s.  It  may  be  shown 
that  the  odds  against  his  winnings  not  falling  below  730s.  in 
the  year  are  thousands  to  one.  He  might  count  on  not 
losing  if  he  offered  2s.  a  day  for  the  expectation ;  on  gaining 
materially  if  he  offered  only  Is.  6d.  Now  restore  the  terms 
beyond  the  fourth  toss  ;  and  as  before  let  Paul  have  a  chance 
of  1  in  16  of  winning  8s.,  1  in  32  of  winning  16s.,  and  so  on. 
There  will  reappear  prospects  which  cannot  be  fitted  into  a 
"  series  ".  A  fortiori  if  the  number  of  days  on  which  the 
trial  is  made  were  smaller.  In  such  a  case  it  is  rightly  de- 
cided, I  think,  by  Mr.  Keynes  that  "  even  if  we  are  able  to 
range  goods  in  order  of  magnitude  and  also  their  probabilities 
in  an  order  of  magnitude,"  yet  it  does  not  follow  that  the 
product  of  each  good  and  the  corresponding  probability  is  the 
measure  of  expediency,  or  "  oughtness".  "A  new  direct 
judgment "  may  be  required  to  combine  properly  the  judg- 
ment of  goodness  and  the  judgment  of  probability  (p.  316). 

Now  to  which  type,  the  Petersburg  problem  or  our 
curtailed  version  thereof,  do  actions  in  real  life  belong  mostly  ? 
The  former  is  certainly  altogether  unparalleled.  The  latter 
too  appears  extreme  in  the  opposite  sense.  "  Series,"  and 
still  less  "  cross-series/'  are  not  so  perfect  as  to  make  the 
realisation  of  the  mathematical  expectation  a  practical 
certainty.  In  private  life  occasions  occur  requiring  that  we 
should  act  for  the  nonce  so  to  speak,  or  at  least  without 
anticipating  a  succession  of  similar  actions  which  would 
afford  a  practical  certainty  of  advantage  in  the  long  run.  In 
public  life  the  same  sort  of  choice  may  occur.  Two  persons 
may  agree  as  to  the  ends  which  are  desirable.  •  They  may 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  CHANCE.  279 

agree  too  as  to  the  probability  that  certain  means,  say  some 
very  progressive  measure,  will  bring  about  the  desired  ends. 
Yet  they  may  differ  as  to  the  advisability  of  adopting  those 
means.  One  may  think  the  other  a  fool.  But  there  is  no 
recognised  canon  of  wisdom  whereby  to  test  folly  in  such 
cases.  Utilitarian  philosophy  has  been  too  silent  about  this 
difficulty. 

CONCLUSION. 

As  the  outcome  of  the  preceding  discussions  the  following 
summary  answers  to  the  enquiries  stated  at  the  outset  are  in 
conclusion  submitted : — 

(1)  That  probability  in  general  presents  gradations  has 
not  been  disproved.  It  seems  usually  possible  to  arrange 
probabilities  relating  to  different  cases,  if  in  eodem  genere,  in 
an  order  of  magnitude,  to  say  that  one  is  greater  than 
another.  The  examples  adduced  by  Mr.  Keynes  show, 
indeed,  that  the  degrees  of  belief  are  often  few  and  far  from 
fine.  Thus  when  we  cannot  forecast  the  weather,  the  baro- 
meter being  high  but  the  clouds  black,  when  accordingly  we 
hesitate  between  the  actions  proper  to  rain  and  to  fair 
weather  (Keynes,  p.  30),  is  not  our  state  of  belief  intermediate 
between  two  degrees  of  practical  certitude  :  that  it  either  will 
or  will  not  rain  ?  Outside  these  degrees  lie  in  general  the 
two  extreme  limits  formed  by  absolute  or  mathematical 
certainty,  denoted  respectively  by  0  and  1.  With  respect  to 
position  on  this  sort  of  scale,  probabilities  which  are  not  in 
eodem  genere,  for  example  the  probabilities  of  two  propositions 
of  which  one  rests  more  on  number  of  observations,  the 
other  on  completeness  of  analogy  (loc.  cit.),  do  seem  to  admit 
of  comparison.  The  question  whether  the  judgment  that 
one  event  is  more  likely  than  another  implies  the  belief  that 
in  the  long  run  that  one  will  occur  more  often  than  the  other 
must  be  answered — if  a  simple  direct  answer  is  required — in 
the  negative.  And  yet  there  is  often  present,  or  apt  to  be 
presented,  some  reference  to  frequency  of  occurrence.  Thus 
in  the  above  instance  of  our  judgment  about  the  doubtful 
prospects  of  the  weather  we  should  be  prepared  to  find  that 
in  exact  meteorological  records  the  observed  signs — high 
barometer  with  black  clouds,  of  a  certain  description — would 
as  often  as  not  (in  the  same  locality  and  season  and  ceteris 
paribus)  be  followed  by  rain  as  by  fair  weather.  According 
as  probabilities  are  more  finely  graduated  and  more  fully 
based  on  statistical  experience  the  determination  of  that 
degree  of  probability  which  it  is  proper  to  attach  to  given 


280  F.  T.  EDGKEWOKTH: 

evidence  approaches  the  character  of  objective  science. 
Otherwise  our  judgments  about  probabilities  have  only  that 
sort  of  universality  which  belongs  to  the  standard  of  taste  in 
art. 

(2)  New  light  is  thrown  by  Mr.  Keynes  on  the  a  priori 
probabilities,  sometimes  ascribed  to  the  Principle  of  Sufficient 
Reason,  which  play  a  considerable  part  both  in  social  science 
and  in  Physics.     He  strengthens  the  defence  of  these  pro- 
positions against  Dr.  Venn's  polemic.     At  the  same  time  Mr. 
Keynes  exhibits  and  guards  against  the  errors  and  exaggera- 
tions to  which  the  Principle  of  Sufficient  Eeason  has  often 
led.     He  confirms  by  a  new  argument  (p.  381)  the  objection 
that,   if   (as   commonly  assumed   in  dealing  with  errors-of- 
observation)  one  value  of   a  measurable  object  is   as  likely 
a  priori  to  be  the  true  one  as  another,  then  any  function  (e.g., 
the  square  or  the  square-root)  of  that  object — or  any  function 
(other  than  simple  addition)  of  two  or  more  magnitudes  (e.g. 
their  product) — will  not  comply  with  assumption.     One  value 
of  the  function  will  not  be  a  priori  as  probable  as  another. 
And  yet  the  function  of  an  object  is  itself  an  object.     If  we 
supposed  that  for  each  kind  of  variable — length,  area,  angle, 
and  so  forth  in  each  variety  of  circumstance — there  is  some 
function  of  the  measurable  object  which  has  a  priori  equally 
distributed  values,  we  might  understand  equi-probability  of 
distribution  as  true  in  a  sense  on  the  average  of  all  cases. 
But  it  is  sufficient  to  postulate  in  each  case  that  the  &  priori 
values   are   not  distributed   very  unequally.     Any  ordinary 
degree  of  d  priori  inequality  will  be  effaced  by  a  correspond- 
ingly large  amount  of  d  posteriori  observation.     This  efface- 
ment   of   d  priori   evidence   through   the   multiplication   of 
instances  seems  to  justify  the  "Rule  of  Succession"  when 
employed  as  a  verification  of  induction  based   on  repeated 
observations. 

(3)  Dealing  with  the  Logic  of  Statistics,  Mr.  Keynes  re- 
affirms effectively  the  important  truth  that  the  Methods  of 
Induction  are  largely  dependent  on  pre-existent  knowledge. 
Part  of  the  "  abstract  and  essence  of   past  experience,"  to 
use  the  phrase  of  Dr.  Marshall,  is  the   circumstance   that 
lines  of  investigation  often  do  not  cross  each  other.     There 
are  water-tight  compartments  in  Nature.     The  chemist  may 
perform  his  experiments  without  attending  to  the  conjunc- 
tures of  the  planets.     This  character  of  natural  law  seems 
closely  connected  with  that  independence  which  plays  a  great 
part  in  Probabilities.     Independence  is  the  prime  condition 
for  the  fulfilment  of  that  "law  of  error"  (or  deviation  of 
magnitudes  from  their  average)  which  Quetelet  and  Galton 


THE   PHILOSOPHY  OF   CHANCE.  281 

have  celebrated.  That  an  ap^  so  little  Baconian  as  Mr. 
Keynes'  "  atomic  character  of  natural  law  "  should  support  a 
generalisation  so  positive  and  matter-of-fact  as  the  fulfilment 
of  an  arithmetically  expressed  formula  by  objects  in  Nature 
is  a  paradox  deserving  the  attention  of  philosophers. 

(4)  The  use  of  mathematical  Expectation  as  a  guide  to 
conduct  is  not  barred  by  the  difficulty  of  obtaining  precise 
data.  Nor  does  much  practical  importance  attach  to  a  scruple 
which  may  be  expressed  by  reference  to  error s-of-observation, 
as  follows.  For  the  purpose  of  measuring  an  object  we 
ought  (a)  to  prefer  that  instrument  or  method  of  which  the 
precision  or  worth  is  greatest.  Supposing  now  that  this 
worth  is  inferred  from  the  behaviour  of  the  compared  instru- 
ments or  methods  in  the  course  of  experience  prior  to  the 
measurement  in  hand,  we  ought  (6)  to  prefer  that  one  for 
which  the  worth  is  most  accurately  ascertained  ;  other  things 
and  in  particular  the  preference  prescribed  under  head  (a) 
being  the  same.  But  what  if  as  between  two  alternatives 
one  excels  in  respect  of  (a),  the  other  of  (6) !  Much  more 
serious  is  the  difficulty  which  arises  when  we  have  to  pre- 
scribe for  action  which  cannot  be  regarded  as  part  of  a 
"  series  " — a  long  run  in  the  course  of  which  the  Expectation 
will  be  realised.  This  djropia  forms  the  main  (though  not 
the  only)  interest  of  the  Petersburg  problem.  Mr.  Keynes 
well  argues  that  some  principle,  other  than  mathematical 
Expectation,  is  required  as  the  guide  of  conduct  in  such 
circumstances.  Utilitarian  philosophy  has  not  hitherto 
furnished  such  a  principle. 

There  are  many  other  points  in  Mr.  Keynes'  treatise  which 
call  for  notice.  But  I  am  not  writing  a  review  of  the  treatise  ; 
only  examining  how  far  the  novelties  therein  require  modifi- 
cation of  my  own  previously  expressed  views.  I  will,  how- 
ever, mention  some  of  the  topics  passed  over ;  in  the  hope 
that  they  may  be  discussed  by  some  of  the  philosophers  who 
read  MIND. 

I  have  already  alluded  to  an  investigation  which  I  did  not 
follow  up,  that  which  relates  to  the  use  of  Analogy  (Keynes, 
Part  III.).  Another  promising  enquiry  relates  to  the  nature 
and  measurement  of  Kisk.  What  value  attaches  to  the 
"  conventional  coefficient  of  weight  and  risk"  given  in  this 
connexion  ?  (p.  315).  This  is  one  of  the  many  questions 
concerning  the  use  of  scientific  language  which  confront 
this  reader  of  the  treatise.  What  is  the  value  of  the 
Symbolism  which  pervades  the  book?  Is  it  as  helpful  to 
the  student  of  Probabilities  as  mathematical  symbols  are  to 
the  student  of  Economics  ?  In  making  this  comparison  the 


282  F.  Y.  EDGEWOKTH: 

mathematician  must  take  into  account  that  in  the  one  caser 
that  of  mathematical  economics,  he  already  knows  the 
symbolic  language ;  whereas  in  the  present  case  he  has  the 
trouble  of  learning  a  new  language.  What  advantage  is 
obtained  by  proposed  changes  of  nomenclature ;  in  particular 
the  peculiar  use  of  the  term  "  correlation,"  and  the  attribu- 
tion of  probability  to  the  truth  of  a  proposition  rather  than 
the  arrival  of  an  event?  Many  interesting  questions  are 
suggested  by  the  rehandling  of  classical  problems.  Thus 
with  regard  to  the  application  of  Probabilities  to  Testimony, 
when  Mr.  Keynes  argues  that  in  certain  cases  the  "  conven- 
tional formula  "  is  admissible,  does  he  materially  reduce  the 
"  opprobrium  of  mathematics  "  which  Mill  attributes  to  the 
classical  theory  of  testimony  ?  Would  Mr.  Keynes  stand  by 
the  answer  which  he  gives  to  the  argument  used  by  De 
Morgan  after  Laplace  concluding  that  "  there  was  a  neces- 
sary cause  in  the  formation  of  the  solar  system  for  the 
inclinations  being  what  they  are "  (so  nearly  identical)  ? 
"  The  answer  to  this,"  says  Mr.  Keynes,  "was  pointed  out 
by  D'Alembert "  .  .  .  "  De  Morgan  could  have  reached  a 
similar  result  whatever  the  configuration  might  have  been  " 
(pp.  293-294).  A  whole  host  of  questions  are  raised  by  the 
author's  criticism  of  his  predecessors. 

I  cannot  pass  over  as  irrelevant  to  the  present  study  the 
topics  included  in  the  last  comprehensive  heading.  I  cannot 
consistently  with  views  above  expressed  appear  to  acquiesce 
in  the  frequent  disparaging  remarks  and  occasional  sweeping 
denunciations  which  the  author  bestows  on  his  eminent  pre- 
decessors. Laplace,  Poisson,  Quetelet,  Cournot,  Mill,  Jevons, 
and  many  others,  even  his  favourite  author  Lexis  in  one 
passage  at  least  (p.  401),  all  according  to  him  have  gone 
astray.  I  find  it,  indeed,  necessary  to  defend  myself  against 
the  imputation  of  attaching  too  much  importance  to  the 
opinions  of  one  who  attaches  so  little  importance  to  the 
opinions  of  the  leading  authorities  on  the  subject.  The  im- 
putation would  no  doubt  be  serious  with  respect  to  some 
sciences.  But  it  is  a  peculiarity  of  our  study,  one  which  it 
shares  with  economics,  that  you  can  retain  respect  for  one 
who  speaks  disrespectfully  of  high  authorities.  In  explana- 
tion of  this  peculiarity  it  may  be  remarked  that  the  classical 
writers  in  both  subjects  often  express  themselves  carelessly. 
Bicardo,  as  Dr.  Marshall  has  said,  was  too  spare  of  words. 
He  did  not  always  duly  emphasise  the  distinction  between 
long  and  short  periods.  He  left  it  to  be  inferred  that  he 
understood  the  part  played  by  Demand  in  the  determination 
of  Value.  Similarly  Poisson  in  a  passage  criticised  by  Mr. 


THE   PHILOSOPHY  OF   CHANCE.  283" 

Keynes  (p.  348)  omits  from  his  statement  of  a  problem  a 
condition  which  was  obviously  present  to  his  mind.  Laplace 
and  some  of  his  followers  probably  understood  the  nature  of 
antecedent  probabilities  and  the  necessity  of  taking  them 
into  account  better  than  might  be  supposed  from  their  ellip- 
tical expressions.  In  criticising  the  classical  writers  some 
"  generosity,"  in  Dr.  Marshall's  phrase,  is  required.  But 
while  preaching  literary  generosity  let  us  not  be  unjust  to 
those  who  are  deficient  in  that  quality.  We  must  admit 
that  intellectual  sympathy  does  not  always  go  with  origin- 
ality. Of  wide  application  is  what  Jevons  said  of  some 
censorious  genius  :  his  own  opinions  are  much  more  valuable 
than  his  opinions  about  other  people's  opinions.  Censorious- 
ness  is  especially  venial  when  it  refers  to  faults  not  inferred 
from  omission,  but  actually  committed.  The  distinguished 
living  economist  who  thought  it  worth  while  to  point  out 
(among  other  criticisms  of  the  classical  economists)  that  a 
passage  in  Mill's  chapter  on  Kent  (Pol.  Econ.,  Book  II.,  ch. 
xvi.,  §  3,  par.  1)  is  inaccurate  remains  a  distinguished 
economist.  Some  of  Mr.  Keynes'  criticisms  seem  to  be  of 
this  type;  not  damaging  much  the  reputation  of  either 
author  or  critic.  A  parallel  to  Mr.  Keynes'  depreciation  of 
Laplace  may  be  found  in  the  work  of  an  original  econ- 
omist whom  Mill  praises  highly  for  his  illuminating  views  on 
Capital,  Dr.  John  Kae.  Like  Mr.  Keynes,  Kae  does  not 
mince  his  expressions  of  dissent.  "  Unsoundness  of  the 
system  maintained  in  the  Wealth  of  Nations  "  .  .  .  "detected 
fallacy  in  the  speculations  even  of  Adam  Smith  "  .  .  .  "  funda- 
mental error  in  the  general  principles  of  his  system  "... 
"  inconsistencies  and  contradictions  "  ..."  all  along  errone- 
ous"— such  are  among  the  expressions  referring  to  the 
Father  of  Political  Economy.  And  yet  Eae  is  praised  in  the 
highest  terms  by  J.  S.  Mill.  Mill's  words  may  be  trans- 
ferred, with  the  alteration  of  a  name  only,  Laplace  being 
substituted  for  Adam  Smith,  to  the  case  before  us.  "  The 
author  unites  much  knowledge,  an  original  vein  of  thought,. 
a  considerable  turn  for  philosophical  generalities.  .  .  .  The 
principal  fault  of  the  book  is  the  position  of  antagonism  in? 
which,  with  the  controversial  spirit  apt  to  be  found  in  those 
who  have  new  thoughts  upon  old  subjects,  he  has  placed 
himself  towards  Adam  Smith.  I  call  this  a  fault  (though  I 
think  many  of  the  criticisms  just  and  some  of  them  far- 
seeing).  .  .  ." 


II.— SENSE-DATA  AND   SENSIBLE   APPEAR- 
ANCES IN  SIZE-DISTANCE  PERCEPTION. 

BY  H.  N.  KANDLE. 

BY  sense-datum  or  pure  sensation  seems  to  be  meant  a 
hypothetical  psychical  process  corresponding  to,  or  a  function 
of,  an  elementary  physiological  process.  It  is  usually  ad- 
mitted that  no  one  ever  experiences  a  sense-datum  in  its 
purity,  but  it  is  sometimes  suggested  that  we  approximate  to 
such  an  experience  when  we  break  through  the  habitual 
nexus  of  associates  so  that  the  sensory  element  appears  in  a 
novel  setting :  as,  for  example,  when  we  turn  the  printed 
page  upside  down,  and  regard  the  S's  and  the  8's  in  this 
novel  position.  Certainly  the  sensible  appearance  changes 
under  changed  conditions,  but  it  is  a  question  whether  the 
novel  sensible  appearance  is  ever  any  nearer  to  being  a  pure 
sensation  than  is  the  familiar  sensible  appearance.  It  might 
be  thought  that  the  appearance  of  the  inverted  S  or  8  ap- 
proximates to  the  pure  sensation  because  it  is  a  more 
accurate  representation  of  the  actual  "  retinal  image/'  and 
therefore  can  more  truly  be  described  as  a  psychical  process 
which  is  a  function  of  the  elementary  physiological  process, 
i.e.,  of  the  retinal  image.  I  propose  in  what  follows  to 
consider  the  size-distance  percept  with  special  reference 
to  the  assumption  that  there  are  to  be  found  in  it  sense-data 
as  denned  above. 

I  begin  with  the  phenomenon  of  the  diminished  sensible 
magnitude  of  an  object  in  monocular  vision  when  the  eye  is 
accommodated  for  a  nearer  point.  With  one  eye  closed  place 
the  point  of  a  pen  midway  between  the  other  eye  and  a  page 
of  print,  keeping  the  eye  fixed  on  the  pen-point.  What 
happens,  then,  is  that  the  print  becomes  amazingly  small.  I 
•still  regard  this  as  an  unquestionable  example  of  sensible 
appearance  of  magnitude  varying  in  complete  independence 
of  the  size  of  the  retinal  image,  although  it  was  suggested  to 
l  that  the  shrinkage  could  be  explained  on  optical  prin- 

1  By  Mr.  W.  G.  P.  Wall,  of  the  Indian  Educational  Service. 


H.  N.  EANDLE  :   SENSE-DATA  AND  SENSIBLE  APPEAEANCES.      285 

ciples,  since  the  increased  curvature  of  the  lens  as  ac- 
commodated for  the  very  near  pen-point  must  result  in  the 
image  of  the  print  (beyond  the  pen-point)  now  coming  to  a 
focus  in  front  of  the  retina  instead  of  on  the  retina :  the 
image  thus  formed  in  front  of  the  retina  being  smaller  than 
the  image  which  is  formed  on  the  retina  when  the  eye  is 
accommodated  for  the  print.  Some  blurring  occurs,  such  as 
should  occur  when  an  image  comes  to  a  focus  in  front  of  (or 
behind)  the  retina. 

And  yet  the  explanation  involves  a  difficulty  of  a  funda- 
mental character,  if  offered  as  a  physiological  explanation  of 
the  shrinkage  in  sensible  size,  as  corresponding  with  a 
shrinkage  in  the  retinal  area  affected.  For  the  optical 
'  image  '  of  smaller  size  formed  in  front  of  the  retina,  is  not 
a  physiological  fact  at  all.  The  only  physiological  fact  that 
could  concern  us  would  be  the  image  as  formed  on  the 
retina:  and  this  would  not  be  a  decreased,  but  a  blurred,, 
image.  If  we  are  conscious  of  the  smaller  '  image '  (in  the 
optical  sense),  then  our  '  sensation  of  extensity  '  corresponds 
to  something  which  is  certainly  a  physical  and  objective  fact, 
but  (quite  as  certainly)  is  not  a  physiological  fact.  To  put 
it  plainly  we  should  see  an  *  image  '  which  is  not  on  the  retina 
at  all. 

And  this  explanation  cannot  be  given  of  the  same  pheno- 
menon as  it  occurs  in  binocular  vision, — both  eyes  now  con- 
verging on  the  nearer  pen-point.  The  same  shrinkage  of 
objects  beyond  fixation-point  occurs ;  and  it  is  usually  stated 
that  it  can  occur  without  any  blurring  at  all,  in  the  case  of 
an  observer  who  can  dissociate  near  convergence  from  near 
accommodation  ;  that  is,  who  can  converge  his  eyes  on  the 
pen-point,  and  yet  keep  the  lens  accommodated  for  the  print. 
I  cannot  do  this,  and  therefore  cannot  verify  this  statement. 

Other  examples,  in  which  the  necessity  of  a  '  psychological ' 
as  opposed. to  a  'physiological'  explanation  seems  to  be 
generally  admitted,  are  to  be  found  in  the  varying  ap- 
pearances of  the  visual  after-sensation  according  to  the  plane 
and  direction  of  projection.  "Produce  an  after-image  of  the 
sun,  and  look  at  your  finger-tip :  it  will  be  smaller  than  your 
nail.  Project  it  on  the  table,  and  it  will  be  as  big  as  a  straw- 
berry ;  on  the  wall,  as  large  as  a  plate  ;  on  yonder  mountain, 
bigger  than  a  house.  And  yet  it  is  an  unchanged  retinal  im- 
pression." x  It  is  impossible  to  assign  a  fixed  extensity- value 
to  the  retinal  impression  in  this  case  for  the  image  "  feels  " 
amazingly  expanded  (or  contracted)  under  the  different 

1  James,  Principles  of  Psychology,  II.,  p.  231. 


H.  N.  HANDLE  :    SENSE-DATA  AND  SENSIBLE  APPEAEANCES 

•conditions  of  projection.  The  feeling  of  magnitude  here  is 
certainly  not  a  function  of  the  magnitude  of  the  retinal  im- 
pression. And  a  still  more  striking  case  of  the  determination 
of  the  sensible  appearance  by  psychological  conditions  and 
its  independence  of  elementary  physiological  processes,  is 
provided  by  the  changed  shape  of  the  after-sensation  ac- 
cording to  the  direction  of  its  projection.  If  an  after-sensa- 
tion of  a  cross  with  the  arm  at  right  angles  to  the  upright  be 
formed  and  projected  upon  the  upper  corner  of  the  wall,  the 
cross  is  seen  slant-legged.1  The  retinal  impression  remains 
presumably  the  same  in  whatever  direction  the  eyes  turn, 
but  the  "sensory  value  "  of  the  retinal  after-image  differs  in 
strict  correspondence  with  the  direction  of  the  eye.  The 
"sensory  variation  in  such  figure-direction  percepts  must  re- 
ceive a  psychological  explanation.  Such  illusions  as  the 
Zollner  pattern  and  the  Miiller-Lyer  illusion  provide  other 
familiar  examples  of  psychologically  conditioned  sensible 
-appearances. 

The  fundamental  importance  of  these  facts  for  a  theory  of 
perception  is  not  sufficiently  realised.  They  tend  to  be  treated 
•as  exceptional  cases,  interesting  psychical  curiosities,  but 
essentially  different,  in  their  generative  conditions,  from 
normal  perceptions.  But  so  far  are  such  cases  from  being 
exceptional  that  in  them  sensible  appearance  reveals  its  true 
•character  in  unambiguous  clearness ;  so  much  so,  that  to 
realise  thoroughly  their  typical  character  is  to  achieve  a 
revolution  in  standpoint.  The  common  feature  in  such  cases 
is  the  impossibility  of  finding  any  fixed  '  sense-datum '  corre- 
sponding to  the  retinal  impression.  And  what  is  here  sub- 
mitted is  that  this  feature  is  not  the  exception,  but  the  rule ; 
that  there  never  is  any  fixed  relation  discoverable  between 
an  elementary  physiological  process  and  an  elementary 
psychological  'sense-datum'. 

There  is,  of  course,  nothing  new  in  this  position.  On  the 
contrary  physiology  now-a-days  seems  to  have  advanced 
definitely  to  the  conception  of  the  integrative  functioning 

1  James  (Principles,  vol.  ii.,  p.  283)  points  out  that  "our  retina  now 
holds  the  image  which  a  cross  of  square  shape  throws  when  in  front,  but 
which  a  cross  of  the  slant-legged  pattern  would  throw  provided  it  were 
actually  on  the  wall  in  the  distant  place  at  which  we  look  ".  Elsewhere 
he  remarks  (vol.  i.,  p.  263)  that  "no  object  not  probable,  no  object  which 
we  are  not  incessantly  practised  in  reproducing,  can  acquire  this  vividness 
in  imagination".  You  cannot  therefore  make  the  after-sensation  of  a 
straight  line  appear  bent  by  projection  on  the  angle  of  wall  and  ceiling, 
because  real  straight  lines  never  do  look  bent  under  any  circumstances. 
(Pathological  conditions  in  retinitis  will  distort  an  objective  straight  line, 
see  Myers,  Exp.  Psych.,  p.  227.) 


IN   SIZE-DISTANCE   PEECEPTION.  287 

of  the  nervous  system,  and  physiological  atomism  appears 
to  have  become  as  obsolete  as  psychological  atomism  is  often 
asserted  to  be.  But  popular  psychology  is  still  under  the 
influence  of  a  way  of  thinking  which  the  professed  psycholo- 
gist has  rejected ;  and  perhaps  this  influence,  even  now, 
prevents  us  from  fully  realising  how  the  problem  which 
Hume  set  to  Kant  has  been  changed  by  a  process  of  psycho- 
logical analysis  which  has  gradually  undermined  Locke's 
"  way  of  ideas  " — or  at  any  rate  its  sensationalistic  starting- 
point.  For  to  deny  that  there  is  any  elementary  mental  fact 
which  is  a  fixed  function  of  an  elementary  physiological  fact 
is  to  deny  the  existence  of  the  sense-datum. 

I  turn  now  to  the  assertion  that  there  are  in  consciousness 
primitive  sense-data  corresponding  to  the  retinal  impression 
—direct  feelings  of  retinal  magnitude,  for  example — but  that 
these  are  obscured  by  perception  of  real  size,  or  imagined 
4 'normal  sensible  appearance";  and  that  we  can  by  intro- 
spective effort  or  training  become  aware  of  these  "primitive 
sensibles  "  even  in  cases  in  which  they  are  ordinarily  eclipsed 
by  the  normal  sensible  appearance.  To  put  it  concretely, 
I  cannot  help  "seeing"  the  corner  of  the  ceiling  of  this 
room  as  a  right  angle :  and  yet,  it  is  said,  if  I  had  had  the 
advantages  of  James'  young  draughtsman l  I  should  be  able 
to  "see"  it  "as  an  obtuse  angle:  to  feel  directly  the  retinal 
direction  of  the  lines.  Therefore  the  retinal  direction  of  the 
lines  must  be  present  as  a  primitive  .sensible  element  in  con- 
sciousness, otherwise  the  young  draughtsman  could  never 
learn  to  feel  it  directly. 

So  far  as  I  am  concerned,  I  am  convinced  that  I  cannot 
learn  to  feel  the  "retinal  direction"  of  the  lines  in  such 
cases,  however  hard  I  try.  I  simply  must  see  the  angle  as 
a  right  angle,  and  I  can  only  draw  it  perspectively  by  methods 
of  trial  and  failure  which  are  guided  by  my  knowledge  of  the 
perspective  law  that  the  vertical  lines  which  bound  the  wall, 
being  real  parallels,  must  recede  as  they  get  further  from  me, 
and  of  the  fact  that  the  upper  part  of  the  wall  is  further  from 
me  than  the  lower  part.  If  I  want  to  "  see  "  the  perspective 
effect  I  can  do  it  only  by  visual  superposition, — as  the  artist 
measures  perspective  magnitudes  by  a  length  of  his  pencil 
held  between  eye  and  object.  And  I  see  no  reason  to  suppose 
that  the  artist  may  have  a  capacity  in  which  1  seem  to  myself 
to  be  very  deficient,  of  introspectively  perceiving  the  per- 
spective or  retinal  values  of  objects.2 

1  James,  Principles,  vol.  ii.,  p.  179. 

2  In  the  case  of  magnitudes,  unlike  figures,  there  is  no  difficulty  in  most 
cases  in  becoming  aware  of  a  sensible  appearance  distinct  from  '  real '  size. 


288      H.  N.  HANDLE  :    SENSE-DATA  AND  SENSIBLE  APPEAEANCES 

What  happens  to  the  young  draughtsman  when  he  learns 
perspective?  James  tells  us  that  his  training  consists  in 
''his  learning  to  feel  directly  the  retinal  (i.e.,  the  primitively 
sensible)  magnitudes  of  objects  ".  If  that  were  so  he  would 
never  learn  to  draw  at  all ;  for  there  is  no  such  thing  as  a, 
feeling  of  retinal  magnitude.  His  task  is  in  one  way  very 
much  easier  than  the  task  which  James  would  set  him, — 
easier  in  so  far  as  it  is  at  least  not  impossible  of  achievement, 
— but  in  another  way  much  more  difficult  than  it  is  repre- 
sented to  be  by  the  traditional  sensationalist  psychology. 
For  according  to  this  psychology  all  the  artist  has  to  do  is 
to  forget  his  percepts  'and  attend  to  his  "primitive  sensa- 
tions". There  is  the  picture  all  ready  drawn  for  him  in  two 
dimensions  on  the  retina  of  his  eye, — all  he  has  to  do  is  to 
copy  it  on  a  piece  of  paper.  But,  if  there  is  really  no  more 
than  this  in  the  artist's  cunning,  it  is  surprising  that  mankind 
took  so  many  thousands  of  years  to  hit  on  the  simple  device, 
and  that  even  now  in  many  parts  of  the  world  where  a  fairly 
high  development  of  the  arts  exists  the  laws  of  perspective 
are  very  imperfectly  known.  It  is  surely  impossible  to 
believe  that  the  trick  is  as  simple  as  the  psychologists  would 
have  us  believe, — that  we  need  only  draw  the  curtain  of 
meanings  to  behold  the  fairest  tree  of  art,  whose  fruit  is 
excellent  and  within  the  reach  of  all.  (It  is  hard  to  resist 
the  temptation  to  misquote  Berkeley's  short  and  easy  way 
with  the  mysteries  of  science,  in  this  connexion ;  for  its 
analogy  with  the  psychologist's  short  cut  to  the  pictorial 
arts  leaps  to  the  eye.)  As  against  this  view  that  the  craft 
of  the  artist  is  a  kind  of  ignorance,  or  withdrawing  from 
reality, — a  view  which  reminds  us  of  Plato's  contention  that 
the  painter's  picture  is  twice  removed  from  reality, — 
the  suggestion  may  be  put  forward  (tentatively,  as  not 
being  based  on  any  knowledge  of  the  history  of  the  arts, 
but  rather  as  an  a  priori  presumption)  that  every  advance  in 
the  technique  of  the  draughtsman  must  have  gone  hand  in 
hand  with,  and  been  based  upon,  an  advance  in  science.  It 
was  no  light  matter  to  play  tricks  with  the  third  dimension, 
to  gather  up  into  one  plane  and  spread  upon  a  superficies  the 
depths  of  space,  and  to  translate  the  solid  world  upon  a  sheet 
of  paper.  For  perception  is  apprehension  under  a  tri- 
dimensional  schema,  and  draughtsmanship  the  finding  of 

But  then  the  sensible  appearance  is  never  identical  with  the  perspective 
or  retinal  value.  Vide  infra .  If  the  draughtsman  reproduces  perspective 
magnitude  with  photographic  fidelity,  then  he  reproduces  on  his  paper 
something  different  from  the  sensible  appearance, — something  other  than 
what  he  sees. 


IN    SIZE-DISTANCE   PEECEPTION.  289 

the  correlate  schema  in  two  dimensions.  Nature  no  doubt 
translates  the  former  set  of  relations  into  the  latter,  upon  the 
retina  of  the  eye.  But  it  is  the  former  set  of  relations,  the 
world  in  three  dimensions,  that  is  given  to  us  in  perception, 
— not  its  projection  on  the  retina.  We  have  no  primitive 
sensibles  corresponding  to  the  retinal  impressions.  And  if 
we  would  copy  Nature's  draughtsmanship,  we  must  laboriously 
learn  her  formulae  for  transmuting  the  tri-dimensional  schema 
into  the  very  different  schema  of  two  dimensions. 

The  question  of  the  relation  of  perspective  values  to 
sensible  appearance  brings  us  face  to  face  with  one  form  of 
the  problem  of  the  relation  of  appearances  to  reality  in  per- 
ception ;  and  with  one  form  of  the  question  whether  any  way 
can  be  found  of  dealing  with  appearances  other  than  the 
subjectivist  way  of  putting  their  existence  '  in  the  mind '. 
If  appearance  meant  perspective5  we  could  answer  the  latter 
question  in  the  affirmative.  Reid  thoroughly  appreciated  the 
objective  character  of  the  perspective  sizes  and  shapes  of 
things,  and  his  rejection  of  the  "  way  of  ideas  "  carried  with 
it  the  recognition  that  the  varying  perspective  values  of 
objects  do  not  exist  "in"  the  mind.  The  visual  angles 
subtended  by  things  at  different  distances,  their  visual  super- 
position values  with  reference  to  each  other  at  different  dis- 
tances, are  as  objectively  real  as  their  "  real "  magnitudes 
and  shapes  are, — the  former  have  as  good  a  claim  to  a  place 
in  the  physical  world  as  the  latter  have.  It  is  a  real  relation 
that  lines  from  the  extremities  of  (say)  a  stick  converging  on 
points  at  varying  distances  from  the  stick  will  form  different 
angles.1  And  genuine  perspective,  perception  is  the  perception 
of  such  objective  facts.  It  is  (e.g.)  the  perception  of  the  dif- 
ferent angles  subtended  according  to  the  distance  between  the 
stick  and  point.  "Real"  perception  is  the  perception  of 
another  objective  fact,  viz.,  the  magnitude-relation  of  two 
objects  in  the  same  plane,  or  as  considered  in  the  same 
plane  ;  or  their  contact  value.  There  is  no  reason  to  class 
the  latter  fact  as  objective  and  the  former  as  subjective.  If 
the  former  is  "in  the  mind"  then  the  latter  is  also  "in  the 
mind".  The  former,  or  perspective  size,  has  been  regarded 
as  subjective,  or  'in  the  mind'  because  it  varies;  whereas 
'  real '  size  does  not.  But,  of  course,  perspective  size  is 

1  There  is  therefore  nothing  to  prevent  a  blind  man  from  understanding 
perspective.  Cp.  the  "  Caecus  duo  bacilla  tenens  "  of  Descartes,  quoted  in 
Berkeley's  appendix  to  the  second  edition  of  his  New  Theory  of  Vision  : 
Fraser's  Berkeley  t^vol.  i.  (1871),  p.  109.  His  sensory  language  may  be 
*  kinaesthetic/  a  language  of  pushes  and  strains ;  but  the  meaning  is  con- 
veyed just  the  same. 

19 


290       H.  N.  HANDLE  :    SENSE-DATA  AND  SENSIBLE  APPEAEANCES 

invariable  in  precisely  the  same  sense  in  which  real  size  is 
invariable.  And  the  facts  perceived  constitute  as  good  a 
reality  in  the  case  of  perspective,  as  in  the  case  of  'real/ 
magnitude. 

The  confusion  between  this  sort  of  relativity  (which  is 
inherent  in  the  objective  reality  of  the  thing)  with  the  other 
sort  of  relativity  (subjectivity)  seems  to  have  come  about  in 
the  case  of  perspective  because  perspective  has  been  (un- 
justifiably) identified  by  psychologists  with  bare  sensation 
of  retinal  magnitude  or  directions.  The  perspective  magni- 
tude has  been  put  first  of  all  in  the  eye;  and  then  in  the 
mind.  The  artist,  James  has  told  us,  learns  to  feel  directly 
the  "retinal  (i.e.,  the  primitively  sensible)  magnitudes  of 
objects  ".  You  first  call  the  perspective  magnitude  "  retinal  "  : 
then  you  call  it  "  primitively  sensible".  The  perspective 
magnitude  is  now  in  your  head, — in  your  mind  :  a  sensation. 
And  so  the  field  of  perception  comes  to  be  divided  into  (a)  real 
sizes  and  shapes,  outside  the  mind,  (6)  perspective  "distor- 
tions," which,  as  identified  with  sense-data,  are  inside  the 
mind. 

But  the  perceptual  world  cannot  long  remain  in  the  un- 
comfortably divided  condition  to  which  this  in-and-out  theory 
would  reduce  it;  and  the  "real"  magnitudes  and  shapes  of 
things  will  effect  an  entry  into  the  mind  along  with  the 
sense-data,  once  the  door  is  opened.  For  "sensation"  is 
the  door  by  which  the  world  gets  into  the  mind,  and  unless 
theory  of  knowledge  succeeds  in  establishing  a  no-thorough- 
fare here,  it  will  never  keep  the  world  at  its  proper  distance. 
It  is  because  we  are  convinced  of  this  that  we  would  keep 
primitive  sensations  of  retinal  magnitudes  out  of  our  analysis 
of  size-perception,  if  we  can  do  so  without  misreporting  the 
facts. 

We  can  see  both  '  real '  magnitudes  and  shapes,  and  pers- 
pective magnitudes  and  shapes.  Perspective  magnitudes, 
though  they  are  not  normal  objects  of  visual  perception, 
nevertheless  are,  or  can  become,  objects,  just  as  much  as 
"real  "  sizes  and  real  shapes.  But  it  is  not  possible  by  any 
effort  of  psychological  analysis  or  any  amount  of  psycho- 
logical training  to  find  the  perspective  distortion  in  the  form 
of  a  primitive  sense-datum,  underlying  the  perception  "in 
your  mind  ".  There  is  no  such  sense-datum  in  your  mind, 
and  therefore  you  will  not  find  it  there.  But  there  are 
perspective  relations  in  the  external  world,  and  if  you  want 
to  find  them  it  is  outwards  that  you  must  direct  your  atten- 
tion, not  inwards :  into  the  world,  not  into  the  mind. 

Simple  observation  alone  will  not  discover  in  most  cases, 


IN   SIZE-DISTANCE   PERCEPTION.  291 

"how  things  really  look," — as  we  wrongly  express  it, — and 
if  we  want  to  realise  correct  perspective  values,  we  shall  have 
to  fall  back  on  an  experiment  of  visual  superposition.  It 
sounds  paradoxical  to  say  that  we  do  not  see  the  perspective 
appearances, — that  we  do  not  see  "how  things  really  look  ". 
But  it  is  the  simple  truth  :  and  the  suggestion  of  paradox  is 
wholly  due  to  the  somewhat  unfortunate  phraseology  of  the 
distinction  between  "appearances"  and  "realities".  It 
would  be  better,  instead  of  "  appearances  "  (in  this  sense)  to 
speak  of  perspective  values  or  effects.  But  it  is  difficult  to 
find  any  acceptable  phrase  which  would  serve  as  a  substitute 
for  "real,"  as  opposed  to  perspective,  size  and  shape. 
Berkeley  substitutes  '  tangible  '  for  '  real ' ;  identifying  visible 
with  perspective.  But  this  phraseology  could  not  be  adopted 
without  accepting  the  more  objectionable  features  in  his 
theory  of  vision.  And  yet  there  is  an  instinct  for  truth 
underlying  his  identification  of  real  with  tangible  magnitudes 
and  figures.  For  the  criterion  of  "real"  size  is  contact,  so 
that  instead  of  real  size,  one  might  perhaps  use  the  phrase 
contact-size.  But  contact-size  is  not  the  same  as  tangible 
size,  though  the  words  are  derivatives  from  the  same  stem : 
for  "  touch  "  has  obviously  different  senses  when  we  speak  of 
two  objects  touching  one  another  and  when  we  speak  of  our- 
selves as  perceiving  objects  by  touch.  Berkeley's  tangible 
magnitude  strictly  interpreted  refers  to  the  latter  :  and  this 
may  be  as  much  a  '  mere  appearance '  as  visible  magnitude 
may  be.  We  may  perceive  real  (or  contact)  magnitude 
through  touch,  just  as  we  may  through  sight :  but  sometimes 
at  any  rate  what  is  perceived  through  touch  is  a  mere  ap- 
pearance, and  there  is  no  guarantee  that  the  magnitude  as 
felt  will  be  real. 

The  identification  of  sensible  appearances  with  the  real 
perspective  values  of  objects,  which  seems  to  be  very 
generally  made,  has  no  grounds  beyond  the  assumption 
(itself  false)  that  retinal  impressions  have  a  fixed  sensory 
value.  It  seems  then  to  follow  from  this  assumption  that, 
as  the  retinal  impression  is  a  true  representation  of  the 
perspective  value  of  the  object,  so  must  the  sensible  ap- 
pearance be, — the  sensible  appearance  (or  at  any  rate  the 
primitive  sense-datum)  being  regarded  as  a  fixed  function  of 
the  retinal  impression.  But  the  facts  are  obvious  enough, 
and  they  afford  conclusive  evidence  that  sensible  appearances 
do  not  correspond  with  actual  perspective  magnitudes.1 

1  James  clearly  recognises  that  "we  end  by  ascribing  no  absolute  im- 
port whatever  to  the  retinal  space-feeling  which  afc  any  moment  we  may 
receive.  So  complete  does  this  overlooking  of  retinal  magnitude  become 


292       H.  N.  HANDLE  :    SENSE-DATA  AND  SENSIBLE  APPEABANCES 

I  look  out  of  my  window  and  see  one  of  the  arches  of  the 
verandah  through  it.  The  perspective  breadth  of  the  arch  is 
visually  superposed  by  about  half  the  breadth  of  the  window. 
A  piece  of  pencil  is  lying  on  the  table — I  judge  that,  if  I 
lifted  it,  it  would  superpose  twice  upon  the  arch.  I  make 
the  experiment  and  find  to  my  no  small  surprise  that  half 
the  pencil  covers  the  whole  arch.  As  for  the  relation  between 
the  window  and  the  pencil,  the  window  looks  so  much  bigger 
that  it  seems  useless  to  judge, — however  I  make  an  estimate, 
and  judge  that  five  or  six  pencil-lengths  will  completely  fill 
the  window  in  visual  superposition.  On  trial  I  find  that 
about  once  and  one-third  the  pencil  length  fills  the  window. 

The  amount  of  error  made  in  unsophisticated  guessing  of 
visual  superposition-values  would  be  a  suitable  subject  for 
experimental  enquiry.  If  I  can  generalise  from  my  own  case, 
there  would  be  a  large  and  constant  over-estimation  of  the 
visual  superposition-value  of  things  further  off,  with  reference 
to  things  nearer.  But  the  point  I  wish  to  bring  out  is  that 
the  "  visible  magnitude  "  of  objects  is  ordinarily  neither  their 
perspective  (visual  superposition)  value,  nor  their  "real" 
(contact)  value, — but  something  in  between  perspective- 
magnitude  and  contact-magnitude.  Visual  magnitude  is  in 
fact  a  compromise  between  perspective  size  and  "real "  size. 
It  is  neither  a  fixed  function  of  visual  angles,  nor  is  it  a  fixed 
function  of  "  real  "  magnitude.  It  tries  to  be  both,  perhaps ; 
but  manages  to  be  neither.  At  any  rate  it  seems  clear  that 
in  such  cases  there  are  not  merely  two  things,  viz. :  (a)  "  real," 
and  (Z>)  perspective  magnitude ;  but  three  things  (a)  real 
magnitude,  (6)  sensible  magnitude,  and  (c)  perspective  magni- 
tude. 

Real  magnitude  and  perspective  magnitude  are  both  alike 
objective  or  physical  facts.  Visual  magnitude  in  most  cases 
does  not  correspond  to  any  objective  fact*  JBut  on  the  other 
hand,  visual  magnitude  is  certainly  not  a  pure  sensation,  or 
sense-datum.  This  is  where  psychology  from  Locke  on- 
wards has  so  consistently  gone  astray.  Take  for  instance 
Berkeley's  distinction  between  "pictures"  and  "images  "  as 
expounded  in  his  New  Theory  Vindicated,  of  which  I  shall 
speak  in  more  detail  below.  Berkeley  assumes  without 
argument  that  the  "picture"  is  given, — is  a  sense-datum 
simply  proportional  to  the  "image":  and  the  picture,  he 
insists,  is  the  immediate  object  of  vision.  So  that  visual 

that  it  is  next  to  impossible  to  compare  the  visual  magnitudes  of  objects  at 
different  distances  without  making  the  experiment  of  superposition.  We 
cannot  say  beforehand  how  much  of  a  distant  house  or  tree  our  finger  will 
cover."  This  is  exactly  the  fact  referred  to  here.  (James,  vol.  ii.,  p.  179.) 


IN   SIZE-DISTANCE   PERCEPTION.  293 

magnitude  proper  is  simply  proportional  to  the  image :  and 
the  image  is  the  perspective  magnitude. 

This,  as  we  have  just  pointed  out,  is  quite  false.  Visual 
magnitude  is  a  resultant  of  many  determinants,  of  which 
perspective  value  (retinal  impression)  is  only  one  among 
many.  Berkeley  of  course  is  aware  that  things  usually 
present  an  appearance  different  from  their  perspective 
magnitude:  but  he  denies  that  this  sort  of  "appearance"  is 
the  proper  object  of  vision.  It  is  (he  holds)  the  effect  of 
"suggestion," — which  brings  to  the  mind  the  "tangible"  (or 
real)  magnitude,  in  place  of  the  visual  (or  perspective)  magni- 
tude. But,  in  the  first  place  he  has  not  realised  how  in- 
variably the  actual  "appearance  "  (whether  you  regard  it  as 
visual  or  not)  is  something  different  both  from  perspective 
magnitude  and  from  real  (or  contact)  magnitude.  And,  in 
the  second  place,  he  has  not  made  out  a  case  for  any  such 
distinction  as  he  assumes  to  exist  between  the  given  visual 
magnitude  and  the  suggested  tangible  magnitude.  The  truth 
is  that  the  only  "visual  magnitude"  which  introspection  can 
discover  is  never  a  given,  but  always  a  product  of  "  sug- 
gestion "  :  and  that  it  does  not  normally  coincide  either  with 
the  perspective  magnitude  (of  which  he  regards  "visible 
magnitude"  as  a  fixed  function)  or  with  real  magnitude 
(which  he  calls  "tangible"  magnitude,  but  which  would 
more  properly  be  called  contact- magnitude). 

A  very  enlightening  illustration  of  the  nature  of  the 
"  sensible  appearance  "  is  the  apparent  magnitudes  of  the  sun 
and  moon.  We  do  not  always  see  the  sun  and  moon  the 
same  size.  They  look  much  bigger  near  the  horizon  than  at 
the  zenith :  and  the  moon  looks  smaller  when  seen  through 
a  telescope, — (although  in  the  latter  case  the  retinal  image  is 
many  times  magnified, — another  example  of  the  obvious  fact 
that  visible  size  is  not  a  fixed  function  of  retinal  impression). 
These  phenomena  provide  interesting  examples  of  the  tra- 
ditional treatment  of  size-perception.  The  case  of  the 
moon's  looking  smaller  when  seen  through  a  telescope  is 
usually  said  to  involve  a  "secondary  deception,"  the  effect, 
so  to  say,  destroying  its  own  cause.  The  case  is  analysed 
thus :  (1)  the  actual  retinal  image  is,  and  is  seen  as,  larger ; 
(2)  as  an  effect  of  this,  we  judge  that  the  moon  is  near ;  (3) 
this  judgment  of  nearness  makes  us  see  the  thing  smaller, — 
because  if  the  moon  is  so  near  as  it  seems  it  must  really  be 
quite  small,  or  its  retinal  image  would  be  enormously  bigger. 
It  is  supposed  in  fact,  that  the  "  sensation  "  corresponding  to 
the  magnified  retinal  image  gives  rise  to  a  judgement  of 
nearness ;  and  that  this  judgment  of  nearness  then  destroys 


294       H.  N.  HANDLE  :    SENSE-DATA  AND  SENSIBLE  APPEAEANCES 

its  own  cause,  the  sensation  of  largeness,  and  generates  in 
place  of  it  a  perception  of  smallness.  The  converse  case  is 
that  of  the  apparent  bigness  of  the  moon  when  near  the 
horizon,  of  which  the  following  analysis  is  often  given.  The 
image  is  dim,  being  seen  through  a  greater  density  of  atmos- 
phere ;  and  is  seen  over  an  intervening  space  broken  up  by 
trees,  etc. :  both  circumstances  carry  the  suggestion  of  dis- 
tance. But  since  its  distance  thus  seems  greater  than  when 
it  is  high  in  the  sky,  we  cannot  help  judging  that  it  must  be 
bigger  than  usual,  in  order  to  produce  the  usual  retinal  image 
when  its  distance  from  us  (apparently)  has  increased.  And 
so  we  see  it  as  bigger.  There  is  a  "  secondary  deception  " 
here  too, — for  I  actually  see  the  moon  nearer  to  me,  when 
close  to  the  horizon, — presumably  because  (a)  on  account  of 
its  apparent  distance,  (6)  I  judge  that  it  is  bigger  than  usual, 
and  see  it  bigger,  and  so  (c)  I  judge  that  after  all  it  must  be 
nearer  than  usual,  and  see  it  as  nearer  ! l 

There  are  no  limits  to  the  possibilities  of  such  epicycles  of 
explanation  :  but  their  necessity  may  well  be  doubted.  Get 
away  from  the  presupposition  that  we  have  an  immediate 
feeling  of  retinal  magnitude,  and  the  whole  complication 
vanishes, — for  the  supposed  difficulty  does  not  exist  when 
once  it  is  realised  that  retinal  magnitude  as  such  has  no 
sensory  value  at  all, — that  we  are  not  even  aware  of  it.  I 
simply  do  not  know  that  the  "image"  of  the  moon  is 
magnified  through  the  telescope.  There  is  no  primary  de- 
ception, and  consequently  no  "  secondary  deception  " ;  and 
the  percipient  subject  may  plead  not  guilty  to  the  charge  of 
harbouring  this  amazing  tissue  of  lies  in  the  soul.  His  per- 
ception of  the  size  of  the  moon  whether  seen  through  the 
telescope  or  at  the  zenith,  or  on  the  horizon,  is  a  function  of 
the  perceptual  universe  to  which  it  happens  to  belong.  As 
correlate  of  the  universe  which  is  seen  in  the  field  of  the 
telescope  the  moon  becomes  visibly  small.  Why  should  it 
become  small  ?  Because  the  telescope  makes  space  collapse. 
The  moon  looks  smaller  because  it  is  reduced  automatically 
to  the  scale  of  a  new  perceptual  schema.  The  moon  projected 
on  a  nearer  plane  is  the  moon  of  a  smaller  world,  and  so 
suffers  shrinkage  to  match  the  world,  of  which  it  is  a  function. 
Similarly  the  moon  on  the  horizon  looks  bigger  because  the 
perceptual  world  is  a  bigger  world  horizontally  than  it  is 
vertically  and  so  needs  a  bigger  moon  as  its  correlate.  The 
over-arching  heaven  is  seen  as  a  very  much  flattened  dome ; 

1  But  sensible  appearance  does  not  necessarily  correspond  with  our 
judgment.  Often  it  persists  when  our  judgment  contradicts  it.  This 
point  is  considered  below. 


IN   SIZE-DISTANCE  PEECEPTION.  295 

and  the  changes  in  the  perceived  size  of  sun  and  moon,  as 
they  climb  to  the  zenith  and  descend  again,  are  proportional 
to  the  flattening  of  the  arch.  It  is  to  be  noted  that  the 
apparent  magnitudes  of  the  heavenly  bodies  obey  precisely 
the  rule  which  governs  the  apparent  magnitudes  of  after- 
sensations.  An  after- sensation  projected  into  a  distant  plane 
looks  bigger,  projected  into  a  near  plane  looks  smaller :  but 
this  is  just  how  the  visible  magnitude  of  the  moon  be- 
haves. It  is  because  the  visible  sizes  of  sun  and  moon  have 
not  been  recognised  as  simple  functions  of  the  perceptual 
schema  that  psychologists  have  been  forced  to  invent  the 
hypothesis  of  "double  deception,"  in  an  effort  to  explain 
their  changing  appearance. 

It  may  be  that  this  '  telescoping '  of  space  is  partly  con- 
ditioned by  a  change  in  the  size  of  the  retinal  impression. 
But  there  is  no  reason  whatever  to  assume  the  existence  of 
a  direct  and  primary  awareness,  or  "primitive  sensibility,"  of 
retinal  magnitude.  The  change  in  retinal  impression,  working 
with  other  conditions,  manifests  itself  to  us,  primarily  and 
directly,  as  a  modification  of  the  general  perceptual  schema, 
a  modification  which  can  be  roughly  expressed  by  saying  that 
things  have  come  nearer,  or  that  a  section  of  space  has  dis- 
appeared, or  that  there  is  a  collapse  of  planes :  so  that  the 
magnitude  of  an  object  as  perceived  by  us  is  never  a  bare 
feeling  of  retinal  magnitude,  but  is  always  the  product  of 
'  relative  suggestion  i.1 

The  supposition  of  perceptual  "  schema  "  as  determinant 
of  the  percept  has  forced  itself  upon  psychologists  in  the 
attempt  to  explain  a  variety  of  apparently  anomalous 
phenomena  of  perception.  Dr.  Myers  puts  it  forward  as  an 
explanation  of  the  phenomenon  of  vision  known  as  auto- 
kinetic  sensation,2  i.e.,  apparent  lateral  displacement  of  seen 
objects  without  eye-movement.  He  makes  the  same  sugges- 
tion with  regard  to  the  size-distance  percept,  in  the  case  of 
the  variable  size  of  the  '  after-sensation '  according  to  the- 
distance  of  fixation-point,3  pointing  out  that  in  this  case 
"  the  subject  does  not  consciously  take  into  account  the  dis- 
tance of  the  fixation-point  ".  He  brings  under  the  same 
category  the  exaggeration  in  the  visual  magnitude  of  familiar 
objects  seen  through  fog,  remarking  that  "both  in  the  case 
of  the  after-images,  and  in  the  case  of  objects  seen  through  a 

1  Stout,  Analytic  Psychology  (1902),  vol.  ii.,  ch.  vi.,  especially  pp.  68-72. 
But  Dr.   Stout  finds  the  starting  point  of  perception  in  "sensory  im- 
pressions which  are  not  themselves  distinguished  and  identified  ". 

2  Text-Book  of  Experimental  Psychology,  1911,  Part  I.,  p.  230. 
8  Op.  cit.,  p.  282. 


296   H.  N.  KANDLE  :  SENSE-DATA  AND  SENSIBLE  APPEAEANCES 

fog,  the  estimation  of  distance  does  not  consciously  affect 
that  of  size.  Yet  primarily  the  apparent  size  must  be  de- 
pendent on  some  unconscious  influence  of  distance.  Possibly 
we  have  here  a  schema  or  unconscious  disposition  in  regard 
to  the  distance  of  objects.  And  when  this  schema  undergoes 
change,  it  manifests  itself  in  consciousness  by  effecting  a 
change  in  apparent  size,  whereupon  the  apparent  size  deter- 
mines our  awareness  of  the  distance  of  the  object."  Similarly 
with  regard  to  the  apparent  sizes  of  the  sun  and  moon,  after 
pointing  out  that  the  form  of  the  sky  is  an  important  factor 
in  the  illusion,  he  states  that  "it  is  this  apparently  greater 
distance  of  the  sky  and  of  celestial  bodies  (at  the  horizon) 
which,  although  not  actually  recognised,  yet  affects  an  un- 
conscious schema,  and  this  leads  to  an  apparent  enlargement 
of  the  heavenly  bodies  where  they  rise  and  set."  l 

The  interest  of  these  passages  is  their  rejection  of  the 
traditional  view  of  the  percept  as  a  working  up  of  given 
sensory  data,  and  their  clear  recognition  of  the  fact  that  the 
sensible  appearance  is  primarily  and  directly  determined,  not 
by  any  "feeling"  of  distance,  or  "feeling"  of  retinal  magni- 
tude, but  by  something  other  than  a  sense-datum, — something 
which  Dr.  Myers  calls  a  schema  or  unconscious  disposition. 
(It  will  be  noticed  that  he  equates  the  behaviour  of  the  after- 
image with  that  of  luna  humilis  and  sublimis.) 

With  a  view  to  elucidation  of  the  determinants  of  sensible 
magnitude  one  turns  naturally  to  the  classical  analysis  of  the 
size-distance  percept  given  by  Berkeley.  It  was  one  of  those 
puzzles  of  size-distance  perception  dependent  on  shift  of 
perceptual  schema  (Barrow's  problem)  which  provided  him 
with  a  starting-point  for  his  New  Theory  of  Vision.  Two 
of  the  principles  of  interpretation  which  he  lays  down  call 
for  mention ;  the  first  because  it  is  true,  the  second  because 
it  is  false.  The  first  is  that  the  conditions,  or  determinants, 
of  size-distance  perception  work  together  to  produce  a  joint 
resultant.2  The  effect  produced  depends  on  the  totality  of 
determinants.  We  should  add,  what  Berkeley  does  not,  that 
any  attempt  to  assign  a  fixed  sensory  value  to  any  one 
determinant,  must  break  down.  "  It  is  not  faintness  anyhow 
applied  that  suggests  greater  magnitude;  there  being  no 
necessary  connexion  between  these  two  things.  .  .  .  Faint- 
ness,  as  well  as  all  other  ideas  or  perceptions  "  (we  should 
prefer  to  say,  conditions)  "which  suggest  magnitude  or 
distance,  does  it  in  the  same  way  that  words  suggest  the 

1  Op.  cit.,  pp.  293-294. 

2  New  Theory  of  Vision,  §§  72  and  73.     Cp.  Stout,  op.  cit.,  loc.  cit. 


IN   SIZE-DISTANCE   PEECEPTION.  297 

notions  to  which  they  are  annexed.  Now  it  is  known  a 
word  pronounced  with  certain  circumstances,  or  in  a  certain 
context  with  other  words,  hath  not  always  the  same  import 
and  signification  that  it  hath  when  pronounced  in  some  other 
circumstances,  or  different  context  of  words."  The  other 
principle  to  which  we  refer  is  that  no  idea  which  is  not  itself 
perceived  can  be  the  means  of  perceiving  another  idea.  From 
this  principle  Berkeley  draws  the  conclusion  that  the  accepted 
optical  explanations  of  size-distance  perception  are  wrong,  for 
"  those  lines  and  angles  mentioned  in  optics  are  not  them- 
selves perceived.  Hence  the  mind  does  not  perceive  distance 
by  lines  and  angles."  The  principle  means  that  the  deter- 
minants of  size-distance  perception  must  themselves  be  facts 
of  a  sensory  or  perceptual  order.  This  is  not  true.  The 
conditions  which  determine  perception  need  not  themselves 
be  sensations  or  sensible  appearances  :  they  may  be  conditions 
precedent  of  any  sensible  appearance. 

The  insertion  of  hypothetical  sensations  (local  signs,  retinal 
•extensity  sensations,  etc.),  for  the  existence  of  which  there  is 
no  trace  of  introspective  evidence,  to  serve  as  connecting  links 
between  (presumably)  nervous  processes  and  perception,  has 
been  carried  by  the  psychologist  to  unjustifiable  lengths.  In 
the  first  place,  as  we  have  said,  there  is  no  introspective 
evidence  for  these  supposed  sensory  elements.  And  in  the 
second  place,  the  supposition  of  them  introduces  gratuitous 
difficulties  into  the  psychological  analysis.  I  am  referring  in 
particular  to  the  insistence  of  psychologists  upon  a  primitive 
sensation  of  retinal  magnitude, — which,  as  we  have  seen,  leads 
to  an  absurd  "double  deception"  analysis  of  certain  size- 
distance  percepts.  We  are  told  that  we  see  the  moon  at 
the  horizon  as  distant ;  and  therefore  we  see  it  as  large ;  and 
therefore  we  see  it  as  near.  This  amounts  to  a  chain  of 
percepts  each  determining  the  next  in  the  series,  with  an 
absurd  result.  Now  there  is  no  introspective  evidence  that 
we  see  the  moon  distant :  and,  if  we  did,  it  would  be  psycho- 
logically impossible  at  the  same  time  to  see  it  near.  The 
only  possible  result  of  such  a  rivalry  of  perceptions  would  be 
an  alternation  of  the  competing  percepts,  with  a  moon  dancing 
a  very  disconcerting  to-and-from  coranto  on  the  horizon.  The 
fact,  however,  is  that  we  do  not  see  the  moon  as  distant,  and 
it  is  false  to  assign  the  percept  of  a  distant  moon  as  the  deter- 
minant of  our  perception  of  a  large  and  near  moon.  The 
determinant  of  perceived  size  in  this  case  (as  in  the  case  of 
the  projected  '  after-sensation  ' ;  and  as  in  the  case  of  shrinkage 
of  further  objects  in  near  vision  when  accommodation  or  con- 
vergence is  effected  for  a  nearer  object)is  the  perceptual  schema. 


298       H.  N.  HANDLE  :    SENSE-DATA  AND  SENSIBLE  APPEAKANCES- 

This  means  that  the  determinant  of  visible  magnitude  is  after 
all  not  a  percept,  but  a  general  shift  of  standpoint,1  which,  so« 
far  from  being  determined  by  a  percept,  is  the  condition  con- 
stitutive of  all  objects  as  perceived  at  the  moment.  The 
schema  is  the  form  of  the  total  experience,  and  is  not  capable 
of  analysis  into  any  set  of  sensational  or  perceptual  elements, 
just  because  it  is  the  condition  underlying  all  the  perceptual 
facts. 

And  here  we  come  to  a  fundamental  divergence  in  the 
behaviour  of  two  different  classes  of  apparent  magnitudes. 
The  size  of  the  moon  is  a  mere  function  of  the  schema,  and 
so  is  the  size  of  visual  after-images.  But  the  size  of  familiar 
objects  seen  through  fog  obeys  a  directly  contrary  rule, — they 
suffer  magnification  instead  of  diminution  when  illusorily 
located  in  a  nearer  plane.  The  same  thing  happens  when 
you  look  across  an  unnoticed  gap  in  the  ground  at  figures  on 
the  other  side.  They  look  surprisingly  bigger  because  a  piece 
of  the  middle  distance  has  been  stolen  and  space  has  collapsed 
upon  the  observer.  In  cases  like  this  objects  refuse  reduction 
to  the  scale  of  a  nearer  and  contracted  world,  in  virtue  of 
what  Berkeley  calls  a  '  praenotion ' 2  or  what  James  would 
call  the  imagined  normal  sensible  size.  (But  the  normal 
sensible  size  in  this  sense  is  not  one  fixed  sensible  appearance 
— "that  which  we  get  when  the  object  is  at  the  distance 
most  propitious  for  exact  visual  discrimination  of  its  details  ".s 
The  normal  sensible  magnitude  of  an  object  is  those  varying 
sensible  magnitudes  which  experience  teaches  us  that  it 
ought  to  have  in  different  planes.)  Familiar  objects  at 
familiar  distances  carry  this  prenotion.  We  tend  to  see  them 
with  their  "normal  sensible  appearance"  at  each  plane  of 

1  How  far  physiological  conditions  of  this  shift  can  be  found  remains  to- 
be  seen.     See  James,  vol.  ii.,  pp.  216-217.      "  The  size  of  the  field  of  view 
varies  enormously  in  all  three  dimensions  without  our  being  able  to  assign 
with  any  definiteness  the  process  in  the  visual  tract  on  which  the  variation 
depends ....  In  general  the  maximum  feeling  of  depth  or  distance  seems 
to  take  the  lead  in  determining  the  apparent  magnitude  of  the  whole  field 
and  the  two  other  dimensions  seem  to  follow.  .   .  .  But  when  we  ask  our- 
selves what  changes  in  the  eye  determine  how  great  this  maximum  feeling 
of  depth  or  distance  shall  be,  we  find  ourselves  unable  to  point  to  any  ona 
of  them  as  being  its  absolutely  regular  concomitant."     See  also  p.  213, 
where  he  draws  attention  to  the  "  sensible  recession  of  the  maximum  dis- 
tance "  which  occurs  on  looking  at  a  landscape  with  head  inveited.     Also- 
pp.  269-270,  footnote.      No  doubt  physiological   conditions   exist :    but 
certainly  they  are  nothing  like  that  " image  on  the  retina"  of  which  the 
sense-datum  is  popularly  supposed  to  be  a  kind  of  literal  point-to-point 
transcription. 

2  Berkeley,  Vindication,  §  59. 
'James,  Principles. 


IN   SIZE-DISTANCE   PEKCEPTION.  299 

projection.  When  therefore  the  figure  of  a  man  in  a  fog  is 
illusorily  projected  into  a  nearer  plane,  our  '  prenotion  * 
assigns  to  the  figure  its  normal  sensible  magnitude  in  that 
plane,  and  we  see  it  big,  as  we  should  see  it  if  it  actually  were- 
as  near  as  that.  And  yet,  in  spite  of  the  unconciously  deter- 
mined shift  of  schema  which  has  thus  determined  the  sensible 
appearance  we  are  aware  that  the  figure  is  really  further  off,, 
and  we  are  surprised  to  find  "  how  big  it  looks  "^ 

The  former  class  of  objects  may  be  called  objects  with 
functional  visual  magnitude,  because  their  sensible  ap- 
pearance is  a  simple  function  of  the  schema  without  inter- 
ference from  any  "prenotions  ".  The  latter  class  may  be 
called  objects  with  normal  visual  magnitude,  because  their 
sensible  appearance  is  determined  by  a  prenotion  of  their 
normal  appearance  at  any  given  plane  of  projection.  The 
principle  obeyed  by  the  one  class  of  objects  is  diametrically 
opposed  to  the  principle  which  governs  the  other  class ;  for 
objects  with  functional  visual  magnitude  (such  as  after- 
sensations,  and  the  apparent  magnitudes  of  heavenly  bodies) 
have  a  visual  magnitude  inversely  proportional  to  the  distance 
of  the  plane  of  projection  ;  while  objects  with  normal  visual 
magnitude  have  a  visual  magnitude  directly  proportional  to 
the  distance  of  the  plane  of  projection. 

Berkeley  lays  stress  on  situation  as  one  of  the  deter- 
minants of  the  size-distance  percept,  and  I  propose  now  to 
consider  the  sections  of  the  Vindication 2  which  set  forth  his 
views  on  this  point.  His  position  is  complicated  partly  by 
the  peculiar  meaning  he  attaches  to  '  image '  here ;  and 
partly  by  the  assumption  which  he  makes  (in  common  with 
most  subsequent  psychology)  of  the  existence  of  "pictures" 
proportional  to  "images,"  i.e.,  sense-data  corresponding  to,, 
and  functions  of,  perspective  projections.  Berkeley  expounds 
the  "image"  and  its  function  by  the  supposition  of  "  a  dia- 
phanous plain  erected  near  the  eye,  perpendicular  to  the 
horizon  (i.e.,  to  the  horizontal  plane)  and  divided  into  small 
equal  squares".  A  line  from  the  eye  to  the  limit  of  the 
"  horizontal  plain  "  passes  through  the  centre  square.  Lines, 
from  the  nearest  portions  of  the  horizontal  plane  pass  through 
the  lowest  squares.  "The  eye  sees  all  the  parts  and  objects 
in  the  horizontal  plain  through  certain  corresponding  squares 
of  the  perpendicular  diaphanous  plain.  Those  that  occupy 
most  squares  have  the  greatest  visible  extension,  which  is 

1 A  case  in  which  "judgment  "  fails  to  dispel  the  illusion.  The  deter- 
minant prenotion  is  working  at  a  deeper  level,  and  a  notion  "  above  the 
threshold  of  consciousness  "  has  no  power  over  it. 

2  New  Theory  of  Vision  Vindicated,  §§  48  to  61. 


300   H.  N.  EANDLE  :  SENSE-DATA  AND  SENSIBLE  APPEAEANCES 

proportional  to  the  squares.  But  the  tangible  (real)  magni- 
tudes of  objects  are  not  judged  proportional  thereto.  For 
those  that  are  seen  through  the  upper  squares  shall  be  judged 
vastly  bigger  than  those  seen  through  the  lower  squares, 
though  occupying  the  same  or  a  much  greater  number  of 
those  equal  squares  in  the  diaphanous  plain."  (They  are  not 
merely  judged  bigger,  but  seem  bigger.  The  visual  idea  is 
"  expanded  ".)  The  'diaphanous  plain  '  is,  of  course,  not  the 
retina,  and  situation  of  the  "image  "  does  not  mean  absolute 
retinal  situation.  Eye-movement  makes  no  difference  to 
situation  in  Berkeley's  sense ;  though  of  course  it  alters 
situation  on  the  retina.  (Any  attempt  to  apply  here  a 
doctrine  of  fixed  '  local  signs/  corresponding  to  retinal  situa- 
tions, as  determinants  of  visual  magnitude,  would  have  to 
take  this  into  account.  The  difficulty  is  perhaps  not  in- 
surmountable. And  there  is  some  evidence  for  the  sup- 
position that  different  situations  on  the  retina  have  different 
magnitude-values, — whether  primitively  or  as  the  result  of 
experience.) 

Berkeley  points  out  that  the  '  images '  and  the  '  diaphanous 
plain'  are  altogether  of  a  'tangible'  nature,  i.e.,  facts  of  the 
objective  or  physical  order.  But  he  holds  that  there  is  a 
psychical  entity — a  visual  sense-datum,  or  'picture'  corre- 
sponding to  these  physical  or  'tangible'  facts.  "There  are 
pictures  relative  to  those  images  ;  and  those  pictures  have  an 
order  among  themselves,  answering  to  the  situation  of  the 
images,  in  respect  of  which  order  they  are  said  to  be  higher 
and  lower.  These  pictures  are  also  more  or  less  faint ;  they, 
•and  not  the  images,  being  in  truth  the  visible  objects.  There- 
fore what  hath  been  said  of  the  images  must  in  strictness  be 
understood  of  the  corresponding  pictures,  whose  faintness, 
situation,  and  magnitude  being  immediately  perceived  by 
sight,  do  all  three  concur  in  suggesting  the  magnitude  of 
tangible  objects  (real  magnitude)." 

It  seems  clear  that  in  this  appeal  to  fixed  situations  on  a 
plane  erected  near  the  eye  Berkeley  falls  into  the  very  pro- 
cedure which  he  condemns  in  contemporary  optical  explana- 
tions of  the  size-distance  percept.1  For  fixed  situations  in  a 
plane  erected  outside  the  eye  are  not  sense-data,  any  more 
than  are  the  lines  and  angles  outside  the  body,  by  which 
geometrical  optics  measures  size  and  distance ;  and  they  have 
therefore  no  proper  place  in  the  sensationalist's  psychology  of 

1  New  Theory  of  Vision,  §§  10  to  13.  His  principle  is  that  "no  idea 
which  is  not  itself  perceived  can  be  to  me  the  means  of  perceiving  any 
other  idea  ".  But  the  lines  and  angles  of  geometrical  optics  are  not  them- 
selves perceived. 


IN    SIZE-DISTANCE   PERCEPTION.  301 

perception.  It  may  be  said  that  the  pictures  corresponding 
to  (retinal)  images  and  situations  are  sense-data.  But  these 
'  pictures  '  are  very  equivocal  entities.  A  '  picture '  may 
mean  one  or  other  of  two  things  (i)  sense-datum,  the  hypo- 
thetical psychical  entity  corresponding  to  retinal  impression  ; 
(ii)  sensible  appearance,  the  product  of  '  prenotions '  and  of  the 
schema.  It  is  really  the  latter  alone  that  could  give  us  those 
fixed  "  situations  "  to  which  Berkeley  appeals.  But  of  course 
Berkeley's  ''picture  "  cannot  be  the  sensible  appearance  (i.e., 
the  suggested  size-distance,  or  the  "  expanded  idea")  for  the 
"  picture  "  is  appealed  to  as  the  bare  visual  datum,  the  deter- 
minant or  suggester ;  and  it  cannot  at  the  same  time  be  the 
determined,  or  suggested,  percept.  What  Berkeley  does  is  to 
make  his  picture  both  these  incompatibles  at  once  :  and  that 
is  why  he  is  able  to  invest  the  "pictures"  with  distinctions 
described  in  the  question-begging  words  horizontal  and 
vertical.  The  sensible  appearances  of  an  already  tri-dimen- 
sional  world  admit  of  these  distinctions.  But  sense-data  do 
not.  And  even  if  we  cut  out  the  reference  to  the  third 
dimension  which  these  words  imply,  and  confine  ourselves  to 
upper  and  lower  situation  of  the  pictures,  the  fact  remains 
that  '  situation '  implies  an  objective  order  as  given.  Berke- 
ley's diaphanous  plain  is  already  objectified ;  and  it  is  this 
objectivity  that  allows  Berkeley  to  speak  of  upper  and  lower 
situation  in  his  '  pictures '. 

The  confusion  arises  because  Berkeley  is  trying  to  get 
done  on  the  level  of  sensory  or  presentational  consciousness, 
work  which  is  already  done  for,  but  not  through,  sensible  ap- 
pearances ;  work  of  which  we  have  presentations  only  in  its 
resultant,  the  sensible  appearance  or  percept.  The  "pic- 
tures" to  which  Berkeley  appeals  here  as  determinants,  are 
already  determined  or  schematised :  they  are  no  mere  raw- 
material  for  thought  to  work  up  into  a  world :  they  are 
already  pictures  of  a  world, — even  if  it  be  only  of  a  world  in 
two  dimensions. 

And,  incidentally,  there  does  not  seem  to  be  any  reason 
whatever  for  supposing  the  existence  of  a  primitive  object  of 
vision  schematised  in  two  dimensions  only.  The  motive  for 
such  a  supposition  is  of  course  obvious  enough, — the  sense- 
datum  is  thought  to  be  somehow  proportional  to  the  retinal 
image,  and  the  retinal  image  is  of  course  in  two  dimensions.1 
Ergo  the  primitive  visual  datum  can  only  be  a  representation 
or  picture  in  two  dimensions.  Distance  is  a  line  turned  end- 
wise to  the  eyes  and  cannot  be  represented  in  two  dimensions 

1  Though  it  is  worth  noting  that  the  retina  is  not  a  plane  surface. 


302       H.  N.  HANDLE  :    SENSE-DATA  AND  SENSIBLE  APPEAEANCES 

on  the  retina, — ergo,  it  cannot  be  '  represented  '  in  perception. 
It  seems  incredible  that  theory  of  knowledge  should  have 
been  dominated  by  so  crude  a  conception,  but  it  certainly 
has  been  so  dominated.  And  the  reason  is  that  psychology 
.accepted  the  existence  of  a  sense-datum  proportional  to,  or  a 
function  of,  retinal  impression. 

A  study  of  the  conditions  under  which  judgment,  or  con- 
scious change  of  viewpoint,  can  alter  the  sensible  appearance,  is 
badly  needed.  The  general  rule  seems  to  be  (and  this  is  the 
only  real  justification  for  regarding  sensible  appearances  as 
something  "  given")  that  the  sensible  appearance  is  not  nor- 
mally subject  to  alteration  by  a  conflicting  judgment.  The 
determinants  of  the  sensible  appearance  must  work  through 
the  schema,  or  general  form,  of  the  experience.  But  yet  there 
are  numerous  cases  in  which  judgment  can  alter  the  percept : 
for  example  those  double-perspective  geometrical  figures 
which  can  be  made  to  assume  one  or  other  of  two  alternative 
.sensible  appearances,  more  or  less  as  the  result  of  a  conscious 
and  deliberate  change  of  viewpoint.  (I  say  'more  or  less,' 
because  to  some  extent  the  appearance  changes  spontaneously 
and  againat  your  will, — an  unconscious  determination  defying 
your  conscious  attempt  to  determine  the  percept.)  But  this 
power  to  determine  percepts  obviously  works  within  narrow 
limits  only :  you  cannot  see  the  straight  stick  thrust  half 
under  water  as  straight,  or  the  moon  on  the  horizon  as  equal 
in  size  to  the  moon  at  the  zenith,  or  five  miles  of  middle  and 
far  distance  as  perspectively  smaller  than  a  few  feet  of  fore- 
ground,— however  hard  you  may  try.  The  sensible  appearances 
have  been  pre-determined,  and  consciousness,  operating  so  to 
speak  externally,  is  powerless  to  interfere  with  them. 

Berkeley's  '  prenotions  '  stand  for  meanings  constitutive  of 
the  sensible  appearance.  As  such,  they  no  longer  exist  as 
merely  separable  meanings  (judgments)  external  to  the 
sensible  appearance :  they  exist  as  immanent  in  and  consti- 
tutive of  the  sensible  appearance.  The  merely  external  and 
separable  meaning  (i.e.,  the  judgment)  may  be,  and  very  often 
is,  contradictory  of  the  immanent  or  constitutive  meaning 
of  the  sensible  appearance.  The  law  of  contradiction  cannot 
prevent  us  from  seeing  one  thing  and  judging  another.  Per- 
ception or  sensible  appearance  is  not  judgment-made ;  though 
it  is  meaning-made. 

The  '  picture '  corresponding  to  the  '  horizontal  image '  of 
Berkeley  is  determined  by  the  prenotion  (immanent  or  con- 
stitutive meaning)  of  the  foreshortening  of  lines  turned  end- 
wise to  the  eye.  If  you  measure  the  perspective  value  of  five 
miles  of  flat  country  against  your  walking-stick  held  erect  it 


IN   SIZE-DISTANCE   PERCEPTION.  303 

is  but  an  infinitesimal  fraction  of  your  stick  that  is  superposed 
•on  the  five  miles  of  landscape.  But  now  incline  your  stick 
into  a  more  or  less  horizontal  position,  endwise  to  your  eyes, 
and  of  course  the  reverse  becomes  true  ;  the  further  landscape 
will  be  beneath  a  larger  part  of  the  stick's  length.  And  that 
is  how  you  see  the  prospect, — you  are  incapable  of  seeing  the 
actual  perspective  value,  because  your  schema  of  perception 
carries  with  it  the  '  prenotion '  of  foreshortening  as  an  im- 
manent meaning  constitutive  of  the  sensible  appearance. 

This  analysis  of  the  size-distance  percept  has  aimed  at 
bringing  out  the  fact  that  the  sensible  appearance  is  in  every 
respect  the  reverse  of  that  hypothetical  entity  the  sense- 
datum, — being,  as  it  is,  the  fluid  product  of  an  elaborately 
constructive  schematism  of  perception.  Starting  with  the 
denial  of  the  sense-datum,  the  analysis  ends  with  the  affirma- 
tion of  the  sensible  appearance.  It  remains  to  emphasise 
some  of  the  points  of  difference  between  the  former  and  the 
latter. 

By  drawing  a  clear  distinction  between  the  psychological 
iact,  the  sensible  appearance,  and  the  psychologist's  fiction, 
the  sense-datum,  we  definitely  reject  that  misleading  psycho- 
logical metaphor  which  makes  of  sensations  or  sense-data  the 
raw  material  of  knowledge,  the  stuff  on  which  the  mind 
operates.  There  is  no  such  stuff  of  knowledge,  no  such  raw 
material,  introspectively  discoverable ;  and,  if  there  were, 
mind  could  not  operate  with  such  refractory  material,  for 
nothing  could  be  done  with  it  beyond  that  combining  and 
disjoining  to  which  (consistently  enough)  the  older  psychology 
confined  the  functions  of  the  intellect.  Reid  observes,1  "  It 
is  a  very  fine  and  a  just  observation  of  Locke  that,  as  no 
human  art  can  create  a  single  particle  of  matter,  and  the 
whole  extent  of  our  power  over  the  material  world  consists 
in  compounding,  combining,  and  disjoining  the  matter  made 
to  our  hands ;  so  in  the  world  of  thought,  the  materials  are 
all  made  by  nature  and  can  only  be  variously  combined  and 
disjoined  by  us  ".  But  in  fact  the  mind  is  an  ariist  whose 
art  is  not  of  this  base  mechanic  order.  It  is  formative  of  its 
own  materials.  Dr.  Stout L/  has  drawn  attention  to  the 
passage  in  which  Hume  admits  the  ability  of  the  mind  to 
supply  a  missing  shade  in  a  series  of  shades  of  a  colour,  in- 
dependently of  previous  experience.3  Hume  remarks  that 


1  Enquiry,  chap,  v.,  §  vii.,  Locke's  Etsay,  II.,  xii.,  1. 

2  Analytic  Psychology  (190;?),  vol.  ii.,  p.  54. 
3 Hume's  Treatise,  I.,  i,  1. 


304       H.  N.  EANDLE  :    SENSE-DATA  AND  SENSIBLE  APPEARANCES 

"the  instance  is  so  particular  and  singular  that  'tis  scarce 
worth  our  observing," — so  blind  could  a  preconception  of  the 
mechanical  nature  of  mental  operations  make  an  acute  ob- 
server, to  the  significance  of  a  phenomenon  such  as  this  of 
'relative  suggestion,'  which  pervades  the  whole  work  of  the 
mind.  The  outstanding  feature  of  the  sensible  appearance  is- 
its  plasticity  and  fluidity,  as  contrasted  with  the  stubborn 
and  superficial  rigidity  of  the  sense-datum.  Its  boundary 
lines  are  not  fixed,  and  there  is  always  more  in  it  than  '  meets 
the  eye  '.  In  view  of  the  infinitely •  complex  cross-currents  of 
meaning  which  carry  and  constitute  it,  the  so-called  image, 
however  determinate  and  '  given  '  it  may  be  at  the  moment 
of  its  appearance  in  consciousness  (and  it  always  seems  to  be 
a  given  and  determinate  thing),  nevertheless  has  more  of 
expression  than  of  impression  in  it ;  and  its  possibilities  as 
expressive  of  the  real  nature  of  things,  are  not  subject  to  the 
limitations  which  the  supposed  impression  (or  sense-datum) 
seems  to  carry  with  it.  In  this  connexion  I  would  emphasise 
the  point  that  the  sensible  appearance  is  not  superficial.  The 
truth  is  that  the  superficies  (the  supposed  sense-datum) 
cannot  be  separated  from  the  depth  of  meaning  which  con- 
stitutes and  underlies  the  sensible  appearance.  The  sensible 
appearance  is  (so  to  speak)  essentially  tri-dimensional.  Indeed 
the  perception  of  the  third  dimension  in  space  is  possible  only 
because  the  sensible  appearance  has  this  '  third  dimension ' 
of  experience,  namely  immanent  and  constitutive  meaning. 
Berkeley's  difficulty  about  the  perception  of  distance,  as 
being  a  line  turned  endwise  to  the  fund  of  the  eye,  does 
really  arise  from  his  reduction  of  the  sensible  appearance 
to  the  .merely  superficial  image.  And  part  of  the  difficulty 
as  regards  the  apprehension  of  substance  is  of  a  similar  order. 
Crudely  put  it  amounts  simply  to  this,  that  the  image  or 
sense-impression  only  reveals  the  outside  or  surface  of  the 
object, — that  we  can  never  hope  to  see  inside  things.  A 
superficial  image  which  has  no  depth  of  immanent  meaning 
might  gives  us  the  qualities  which  form,  so  to  speak,  the 
surface  of  things,  but  it  can  never  give  us  the  thing  in  its 
substantiality,  transparent  in  three  dimensions.  Our  '  senses  * 
can,  no  doubt,  give  us  any  number  of  cross-sections  of  sub- 
stance ;  but  never  substance  in  its  solid  integrity.  But,  in 
truth,  we  do  "  see  "  distance,  and  we  do  "  see  "  things  solid  : 
the  defect  is  not  in  our  sense-perception,  but  in  the  misleading 
analysis  of  sense-perception  into  sense-data. 

Again,  the  sense-datum  is  supposed  to  precede  a  meaning 
which  it  subsequently  acquires;  whereas  the  sensible  ap- 
pearance is  inseparable  from  and  preconditioned  by  the 


IN    SIZE-DISTANCE    PERCEPTION.  305 

meaning  which  it  expresses.  I  can  find  no  reason  to  believe 
in  the  existence  of  a  meaningless  impression.  It  seems  to 
me  that,  logically  and  psychologically,  meaning  is  the  pre- 
supposition and  condition  precedent  of  every  sensible  ap- 
pearance ;  sensible  appearances  being  never  impressional,  but 
always  expressional,  in  nature.  Sensible  appearances  are 
the  language  in  which  the  poetic  faculty  of  mind  tries  to 
find,  under  limitations,  an  expression,  not  altogether  inade- 
quate, for  those  meanings  which  we  call  physical  facts.  The 
sensible  appearances  are  'unreal'  in  so  far  as  they  are  in- 
complete and  inadequate  expressions  of  the  meanings.  We 
have  not  tried  to  show  that  the  sensible  appearance  is  ever  a 
completely  adequate  expression  of  the  real  (for  it  never  is), 
but  only  that  it  is  very  much  more  than  an  *  image,' — that  it 
has  the  plasticity  which  is  characteristic  of  an  effort  to 
express  a  meaning.  But  if  what  Berkeley  delighted  to  call 
the  Divine  Visual  Language  is  charged  with  a  meaning 
greater  than  it  can  express  we  need  not  so  far  detach  and 
"  immobilise  "  it  as  to  make  it  appear  incapable  of  conveying 
any  meaning  whatever.1 

There  is  another  aspect  of  the  difference  between  the  sense- 
datum  and  the  sensible  appearance,  which  may  be  exemplified 
in  the  obvious  fact  that  we  can  perceive  motion :  but  which, 
in  its  fullest  implication,  means  no  less  a  difference  than  that 
between  a  connected  experience  and  a  disconnected  system  of 
floating  '  ideas '.  Experience  is  not  connected  through 
'  ideas '  and  on  the  surface,  but  in  the  depth  through 
meanings, — and  to  confine  it  to  superficial  impressions — 
sense-data — is  necessarily  to  disintegrate  it.  Lockian  '  ideas  ' 
are  but  the  flotsam  of  a  universe  wrecked  on  a  false  psy- 
chology, and  out  of  the  flotsam  popular  psychology  labours 
in  vain  to  reconstruct  the  continuity  of  the  real  world  as 
given  in  perception.  The  entirely  gratuitous  difficulty  which 
is  often  felt  about  the  perception  of  motion,  in  particular, 
simply  arises  from  the  substitution  of  sense-data  for  the  truly 
functional  thought-element,  the  sensible  appearance.  There 
can  be  no  sense-datum  or  impression  of  movement,  because 

1  Cp.  Bergson's  dictum  "  Percevoir  signifie  iminobiliser "  (Matiere  et 
Mtfmoire,  p.  232,  Paris:  1913).  Bergson's  "  pure  percept"  has  a  sus- 
picious resemblance  to  the  sense-datum.  As  Hoffding  points  out  "  Berg- 
son  makes  too  great  and  too  external  a  difference  between  the  immediate 
given  and  the  psychical  activity.  Nothing  is  given  to  us,  no  subject 
arises,  without  psychical  activity,  whether  we  notice  it,  or  whether  we  do 
not "  (Hoffding,  Modern  Philosophers,  English  translation,  p.  247).  But 
Bergson  teaches  the  better  way  of  regarding  perception  in  such  passages 
as  Matiere  et  Me'moire  (Paris  :  1913),  p.  232— "Elle  s'etale  immobile,  en 
surface,  mais  elle  vit  et  vibre  en  profondeur  ". 

L    20 


306      H.  N.  HANDLE  :    SENSE-DATA  AND  SENSIBLE  APPEAEANCES. 

the  sense-datum,  like  the  individual  cinematographic  film, 
stands  for  a  moment  of  rest,  and  though  you  may  attempt  to 
counterfeit  continuity  (as  the  cinematograph  does)  by  filling 
the  interstices  of  your  fragmentary  sense-data  with  an  infinity 
of  sub-conscious  impressions  or  petites  perceptions,  you  will 
never  succeed  in  passing  from  instantaneous  immobilities  to 
a  moving  continuity.  But  there  is  no  reason  why  the  moving 
continuity  should  not  find  expression  in  the  sensible  appear- 
ance, though  it  defies  every  attempt  to  reduce  it  to  a  series  of 
'impressions  of  sense'.  The  sensible  appearance  of  move- 
ment is  a  sufficiently  familiar  experience,  and  one  about 
which,  if  the  psychologist  had  asked  no  leading  questions, 
introspection  would  have  told  no  lies.  It  is  not  wonderful 
that  behaviourist  psychology  should  attempt  to  ignore  con- 
sciousness, as  not  having  any  functional  significance  in  the 
thought-process,  seeing  that  traditional  psychology  has  con- 
fined consciousness  to  simulacra,  which  by  their  immobility 
and  detachment  are  debarred  from  playing  any  role  in  the 
moving  drama  of  experience, — being,  like  Berkeley's  ideas, 
'visibly  inactive '. 


III.— MR.  RUSSELL'S  THEORY  OF  THE 
EXTERNAL  WORLD. 

BY  C.  A.  STRONG. 

IN  his  recently  published  Analysis  of  Mind  Mr.  Eussell 
reiterates  the  neo-realistic  or  phenomenalistic  theory  which 
he  first  developed  in  Our  Knowledge  of  the  External  World, 
but  now  in  the  setting  of  a  sensationalistic  psychology  and 
metaphysics.  As  I  am  in  complete  sympathy  with  such  a 
psychology,  and  have  myself  tried  to  work  out  a  metaphysics 
which  finds  the  type  of  the  real  in  sensation,  my  observations 
in  the  following  article  will  be  made  from  a  near  and  friendly 
point  of  view.  If  he  will  allow  me  to  say  so,  I  admire  his 
psychology  immensely ;  but  I  have  some  reserves  to  make  in 
regard  to  his  theory  of  knowledge. 

I. 

Mr.  Eussell  agrees  with  the  neo-realists  in  holding  that 
matter  and  mind  represent  two  different  ways  of  arranging 
a  single  stuff,  '  experience '  or  '  sensation  ' — namely,  in  per- 
spectives of  physical  objects  and  in  biographies.  He  differs 
from  them,  first,  in  admitting  that  those  perspectives  which 
are  appearances  to  us  human  beings  are  immediately  depend- 
ent on  events  inside  our  bodies,  and  more  or  less  distorted 
by  the  medium  of  nerves  and  brain  through  which  they  are 
perceived ;  whereas  other  neo-realists  hold,  I  think,  that  the 
perspectives  are  accurate  visions  of  things  as  they  exist  out- 
side us.  We  may  be  sure  that,  if  Mr.  Russell  makes  this 
admission,  it  is  because  the  facts  have  been  too  much  for 
him ;  his  natural  tendency  is  to  think  that  the  colours  we 
see  actually  exist,  as  they  seem  to,  in  things  outside  us. 

What  are  the  facts  which  necessitate  this  admission  ? 
They  are,  first,  the  time  and  space  relations  of  visual  appear- 
ances— the  fact  that  they  show  us  events  as  occurring,  not 
at  the  moment  when  they  do  occur,  but  at  the  moment  when 
the  report  of  them  reaches  the  body  ;  the  fact  that  they  show 
us  objects,  not  in  their  true  shape  and  dimensions,  but  as 


308  c.  A.  STEONG: 

they  must  appear  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  body,  i.e.,  with 
a  certain  amount  of  perspective  distortion.  They  are, 
secondly,  such  exceptional  visual  phenomena  as  after-images 
and  muscae  volitantes,  which  show  that  an  appearance,  due 
in  reality  wholly  to  causes  within  the  body,  may  yet  be  seen 
outside  it,  just  as  if  it  existed  there.  These  facts  prove  that 
objects  and  events  outside  the  body  are  conditions  of  what 
is  seen  and  heard  only  indirectly,  and  that  the  one  and  only 
immediate  condition  is  the  event  in  the  nervous  system. 

This  state  of  things,  of  course,  gives  rise  to  the  crux  of 
realistic  theories,  namely,  to  explain  how  a  sensation  that 
varies  directly  only  with  one  physical  object,  the  nervous 
system,  can  yet  -vary  with  another  physical  object  sufficiently 
to  give  knowledge  of  it.  The  commonest  answer  is  that  it 
varies  with  the  nervous  system  only  as  to  its  occurrence  or 
non-occurrence,  but  that  as  to  what  it  shows  us,  i.e.,  the  quali- 
ties and  their  spatial  arrangement,  it  varies  directly  with  the 
object.  The  trouble  with  this  answer  is  that  it  is  in  conflict 
with  the  facts.  The  sensation  does  vary  with  the  object,  in 
all  those  cases  where  it  gives  correct  knowledge  of  it,  but  it 
does  not  do  so  directly  ;  it  varies  directly  only  with  the  brain- 
process,  and  with  the  object  in  case  the  brain-process  varies 
with  it.  If  the  brain-process  does  not  vary  with  the  object 
— as,  for  instance,  when  we  have  taken  a  dose  of  santonin — 
the  sensation  will  give  false  knowledge  of  it,  i.e.,  all  visible 
objects  will  be  tinged  with  yellow.  'And,  in  all  cases,  we 
may  say,  the  sensation  is  better  adapted  to  give  knowledge 
of  the  brain-process  than  to  give  knowledge  of  the  external 
object. 

The  other  common  answer  is  that  you  must  not  pay  any 
attention  to  physiological  facts  when  you  are  discussing  such 
deep  questions  as  the  nature  of  knowledge,  for,  if  you  do, 
you  get  into  difficulties  with  your  intuitive  theory  of  knowing 
and  are  tempted  to  believe  in  things  which  you  cannot  logic- 
ally prove.  Mr.  Eussell  deserves  credit  for  recognising  the 
facts  and  seeking  to  square  his  theory  with  them ;  though 
I  am  not  sure  that  he  makes  any  attempt  to  explain  why 
reality  should  be  tied  into  so  peculiar  a  knot.  Yet  a  rounded 
and  adequate  theory  of  perception  should  explain  not  only 
how  this  function  is  related  to  the  object,  but  also  how  it  is 
related  to  the  brain ;  it  should  account  for  both  these  rela- 
tions of  the  mind  to  matter.  Mr.  Kussell,  I  think,  contents 
himself  with  the  fact  that  perception  is  connected  with  the 
brain,  and  lets  it  go  at  that. 

He  agrees  with  the  neo-realists,  again,  in  holding  that 
objects  continue  to  exist  when  we  no  longer  see  or  touch 


ME.  RUSSELL'S  THEORY  OF  THE  EXTERNAL  WORLD.    309 

them ;  indeed,  he  would  of  course  not  be  a  realist  at  all  if 
he  did  not  hold  this.  But  other  neo-realists,  I  think,  suppose 
objects  when  not  perceived  to  be  exactly  like  what  they  are 
when  perceived,  and  to  retain  the  very  colours  and  the  very 
spatial  arrangement  which  we  perceive  them  to  have.  Mr. 
Russell  cannot  admit  this,  since  the  nature  of  what  we  per- 
ceive is  determined  at  least  in  large  part  by  the  medium  of 
nerves  and  brain  through  which  we  perceive  them  ;  and  he 
therefore  maintains  that  those  perspectives  which  are  not 
given  to  human  beings  or  animals  are  very  unlike  those 
perspectives  which  are.  They  are  still  perspectives,  nota 
bene,  but  they  are  very  unlike. 

We  shall  perhaps  not  misrepresent  him  if  we  say  that,  at 
the  points  of  space  which  are  reached  by  light  from  an  object, 
there  is  something,  of  the  nature  of  sensation,  but  as  unlike 
what  we  see  as  the  physical  process  occurring  there  is  unlike 
the  process  occurring  in  the  brain.  Let  us,  for  convenience, 
describe  this  something  as  a  '  sub-sensation '.  Now,  I  have 
a  difficulty  with  the  notion  that  a  sub-sensation  is  a  per- 
spective. The  formation  of  a  perspective  seems  to  be  im- 
possible without  a  lens,  to  draw  the  light-rays  coming  from 
each  point  of  an  object  together  into  a  corresponding  point 
on  a  retina  or  plate,  thus  forming  an  image.  In  discussing 
sub-sensations  Mr.  Russell  has  mentioned  the  plate,  but  he 
has  not  mentioned  the  lens ;  yet,  without  it,  all  the  points  of 
the  object  (i.e.,  on  this  surface  of  it)  would  send  light-rays 
to  each  point  of  the  plate,  and  all  the  light-rays  would  be 
confused  together,  and  there  would  be  no  image  or  perspec- 
tive. Indeed,  when  we  consider  that  there  are  light-rays 
entering  that  point  from  all  quarters  of  the  heavens,  it  is 
evident  that,  apart  from  such  a  process  of  analysis  as  the 
lens  permits,  what  exists  there  is  only  a  synthesis  of  effects, 
and  not  anything  like  the  stars  from  which  the  rays  pro- 
ceeded. I  can  hardly  suppose  that  Mr.  Russell,  with  his 
competent  knowledge  of  physics,  has  overlooked  this  point, 
and  yet  it  appears  plainly  inconsistent  with  his  description 
of  the  sub-sensations  as  perspectives  or  appearances. 

Since,  however,  the  perspectives  can  by  analysis  be  separ- 
ated out,  let  us  assume,  for  argument's  sake,  that  they  are 
there,  and  that  things  existing  unperceived  are  still  perspec- 
tives ;  and  let  us  come  to  the  central  point  of  the  theory,  the 
definition  of  the  physical  object  as  '  a  system  of  perspectives  '. 
A  table,  on  this  view,  is  not  a  single  thing,  existing  separately 
from  all  the  perspectives  which  you  might  have  if  you  ex- 
amined it  from  different  points  of  view,  but  is  simply  a  name 
for  the  sum  of  these  perspectives.  They  alone  are  ultimate 


310  c.  A.  STEONG: 

constituents  of  reality.  A  star,  in  the  same  way,  is  a  name 
for  all  the  perspectives  of  it,  as  seen,  photographed,  or  not 
even  photographed,  that  are  disseminated  throughout  the 
universe.  And  I  suppose  that  the  nuclear  part  of  an 
atom  is  not  a  bit  of  matter,  hut  a  name  for  the  perspectives 
that  would  appear  to  a  physicist  who  should  invent  a  super- 
microscope  sufficiently  powerful  to  reveal  it. 

What  first  strikes  one  in  this  theory  is  the  curious  reversal 
of  the  spatial  position  of  objects  which  it  seems  to  involve 
— objects  being  apparently  everywhere  except  in  the  place 
where  we  see  and  feel  them.  Thus,  as  you  approach  a  table, 
you  get  a  better  and  better  perspective  of  it  until  you  are 
quite  near,  and  then  confused  perspectives,  and  after  that 
there  is  nothing.  (If  the  perspectives  were  views  of  the 
table,  not  constituents  of  it,  it  would  be  quite  intelligible 
that  we  should  get  them  only  from  points  outside  itself.) 
But  we  must  remember  that,  on  Mr.  Russell's  theory,  space 
has  no  existence  except  as  an  internal  character  of  the  per- 
spectives :  the  continuous  '  public  '  space,  in  which  common 
sense  supposes  all  objects  to  exist,  is  only  a  mental  construc- 
tion. So  that  what  I  have  been  saying  is  not  that  there  is 
a  real  place  with  no  perspectives  in  it,  but  only  that  no  per- 
spectives exist  which  are  views  of  the  table  from  that  place. 
It  is  not  the  less  a  paradox  that  light  should  have  to  proceed 
from  a  place,  in  which  there  is  no  constituent  of  the  object, 
as  a  condition  of  the  arising  of  a  perspective  of  it,  and  yet 
that  the  place  (and,  I  suppose,  the  light  too,  with  its  velocity) 
should  have  no  existence  apart  from  this  or  some  other 
perspective. 

But  the  greatest  paradox  is  that  which  arises  with  reference 
to  time.  To  fix  the  object  at  a  definite  instant,  we  must 
take  as  our  example  of  an  object  an  event.  There  is  a  game 
played  in  England,  of  which  I  regret  to  say  I  have  no 
personal  experience,  called  cricket,  in  which  the  principal 
event  is,  I  think,  the  batting  of  a  ball.  Let  us  take  this 
event,  happening  at  12  o'clock  on  Thursday,  as  our  example. 
It  breaks  up,  on  Mr.  Russell's  theory,  into  a  great  number  of 
perspectives,  partly  in  (or  at  least  closely  connected  with) 
the  bodies  of  the  players  and  spectators,  and  partly  in  the 
air.  Now  each  and  every  one  of  these  perspectives  is  '  late,' 
by  the  time  required  for  the  light-rays  to  pass  from  the 
batsman's  bat  to  the  eyes  of  the  spectators  or  to  the  points 
in  the  air.  They  therefore  all  happen  after  12  o'clock.  The 
paradox,  then,  is  that  a  multitude  of  events,  all  happening 
after  12  o'clock,  should  be  the  constituents  of  an  event 
happening  at  12  o'clock. 


MB.  BUSSELL'S  THEOBY  OF  THE  EXTEBNAL  WOBLD.    311 

It  is  no  use  pointing  out  that  12  o'clock  is  the  mathematical 
limit  of  all  the  perspectives,  to  which  we  are  necessarily  led 
when  we  consider  them  as  a  system :  that  does  not  make 
the  event  at  12  o'clock  any  the  more  real.  Of  course  Mr. 
Russell  may  escape  from  the  difficulty,  with  all  honours,  by 
holding,  as  before  in  the  case  of  space,  that  time  is  only  an 
internal  characteristic  of  the  perspectives,  and  that  they  are 
not  really  themselves  in  time :  but  I  am  not  sure  that  he 
wishes  to  be  as  transcendental  as  this.  Doubtless  his  theory, 
as  thus  interpreted,  would  be  an  accurate  transcript  of  the 
phenomenal  facts  ;  but  solipsism  is  that.  And  it  would  be  a 
a  strange  realism,  surely,  that  maintained  both  that  the 
perspectives  are  not  in  time,  as  they  appear  to  be,  and  that 
the  event  at  12  o'clock  did  not  really  happen. 

We  may  draw  one  inference  from  these  paradoxes,  and 
that  is  that  the  object,  as  physical  science  conceives  it,  is  not 
correctly  denned  as  the  system  of  all  the  perspectives  (even 
of  the  ( regular '  ones,  i.e.,  those  undistorted  by  the  intervening 
medium),  but  is  rather  their  mathematical  limit.  This  is 
evidently  true  as  regards  its  time ;  and  its  shape  and  size 
are  not  those  of  any  of  the  perspectives,  since  these  are  all 
distorted,  but  are  the  shape  and  size  of  that  object  which, 
situated  in  the  place  where  the  object  is  seen,  would  produce 
the  perspectives  on  the  retinas  and  in  the  minds  of  observers, 
according  to  the  laws  of  perspective.  The  physical  object 
is  the  implicate  of  all  the  perspectives ;  its  relation  to  them 
is  somewhat  like  that  of  a  Platonic  idea  to  the  particulars 
which  constitute  its  exemplification.  This  is  why  the  object 
is  felt  to  be  given,  whole  and  entire,  as  it  were,  in  each  per- 
spective. 

This  antithesis  between  the  one  physical  object  and  the 
many  perspectives  exists  alike,  whether  we  regard  the  former 
as  a  real  existence,  or,  with  Mr.  Kussell,  as  only  a  mental 
construction.  It  may  still  be  (so  far  as  we  have  yet  gone) 
that  the  only  existences  and,  so  to  speak,  metaphysical 
supports  of  the  object  are  the  appearances. 

In  any  case,  the  appearances  upon  which  an  object  depends 
for  its  reality  cannot  be  the  visual  ones.  For,  if  they  were,, 
what  would  happen  to  a  table  when  you  turned  off  the: 
electricity  and  left  it  in  the  dark  ?  The  absence  of  light  has 
suppressed  not  only  the  perspectives  in  human  minds,  but 
also  those  inferior  perspectives  upon  which  we  relied  to  give 
continued  existence  to  objects.  And  yet  the  table,  according 
to  common  sense,  exists  just  as  truly  and  just  as  completely 
as  when  the  light  was  on.  Are  we  then  to  be  realists  for 
the  sunshine  and  the  electric  light,  but  idealists  for  the  dark? 


312  c.  A.  STEONG: 

But,  of  course,  there  are  still  the  tactile  appearances  for  us 
to  fall  back  upon. 

These  suffice  to  maintain  the  table  in  existence  so  long  as 
we  actually  touch  it.  But  what  happens  if  we  take  our 
hands  away  ?  What  becomes  of  a  penny  when  you  put  it 
in  your  pocket  ?  Are  there  tactile  appearances  in  immediate 
contact  with  it — for  it  is  only  there  that  tactile  sensations 
are  produced — and  is  it  to  these  tactile  sub-sensations  that  it 
owes  its  continued  existence  ?  Mr.  Kussell  has  not  worked 
out  his  theory  in  detail  for  the  case  of  tactile  appearances, 
and  I  am  obliged  to  proceed  by  surmise.  But,  if  there  are 
such  tactile  sub-sensations,  then  apparently  the  penny  exists 
by  producing  tactile  sub-sensations  in  the  pocket,  and  the 
pocket  in  its  turn  by  performing  the  like  service  for  the 
penny.  We  have  here  another  instance  of  that  curious  re- 
versal of  the  spatial  position  of  objects  which  seems  to  be 
involved  in  Mr.  Eussell's  theory. 

But,  surely,  these  tactile  phenomena  in  the  penny  and 
the  pocket  are  effects,  and  they  imply,  each  on  its  side, 
preceding  causes  in  the  pocket  and  in  the  penny  respectively, 
which  may  also  be  of  the  nature  of  sub-sensations.  Suppose 
what  touches  the  penny  is  not  the  pocket  but  my  hand. 
And  let  the  penny  be  warm.  Now,  physically,  any  warmth 
that  passes  from  the  penny  into  my  hand  and  produces 
sensations  there  is  a  gradual  process,  beginning  in  the  penny 
and  ending  in  my  hand.  One  of  two  things,  then.  Either 
this  process,  so  long  as  it  remains  in  the  penny,  has  no  real 
existence,  and  the  penny,  when  I  put  it  back  in  my  pocket, 
wholly  ceases  to  be.  Or  else  it  pre-exists  to  my  sensations, 
as  their  cause,  and  then,  if  we  adopt  Mr.  Eussell's  meta- 
physical hypothesis,  it  will  consist  of  sub-sensations. 

It  will  be  seen  that  I  have  accepted  this  hypothesis,  and 
simply  put  the  sub-sensations  in  a  different  place :  not  beside 
our  own  sensations,  as  something  bearing  a  similar  relation 
to  the  object,  but  beyond  them,  as  that  in  which  the  being 
of  the  object  consists.  Or,  to  put  it  differently,  I  have 
conceived  them,  not  as  other  appearances,  but  as  that  which 
appears. 

II. 

This,  of  course,  is  something  that  a  philosopher  who  re- 
spects himself  must  not  do.  Sub-sensations,  so  conceived, 
are  things  in  themselves,  and  things  in  themselves  are  un- 
knowable. You  cannot  go  beyond  your  own  sensations,  or 
the  world  as  they  present  it  to  you.  Moreover,  if  you  did, 


ME.  KUSSELL'S  THEOEY  OF  THE  EXTEENAL  WOELD.    313 

you  would  have  two  kinds  of  objects  on  your  hands,  the 
objects  of  experience  and  these  objects  of  fancy,  and  you 
could  not  possibly  explain  how  these  two  worlds  of  objects 
were  joined  into  one. 

The  ultimate  ground  of  this  judgment  is  the  assumption 
that  sensible  appearances  are  themselves  the  objects  seen 
and  touched,  that  they  are  existences,  and  that  there  is  no 
accompanying  element  of  belief,  referring  them  to  something 
other  than  themselves. 

I  shall  try  to  show  (1)  that  appearances  are  not  existences, 
but  only  sensations  in  so  far  as  they  are  used  as  signs ; 
(2)  that  they  are  always  (in  cases  where  they  give  knowledge) 
accompanied  by  belief;  (3)  that  the  belief  is  to  the  effect 
that  an  object  exists,  having  the  characters  which  the  ap- 
pearance shows  us.  This  belief  is  not  a  formulated  one ;  it 
is  only  expressed  in  our  acting  as  if  the  appearance  showed 
us  an  object.  The  object  is  thus  not  inferred  from  the 
appearance,  but  directly  known  through  it. 

Mr.  Eussell  accepts  the  phenomenalistic  principle — as  we 
may  call  the  denial  of  the  legitimacy  of  transcendence — and 
his  theory  is,  in  the  main,  the  application  of  it  to  perception. 
Does  he  adhere  to  it  strictly  everywhere  ?  The  question  is 
pertinent ;  for  a  principle  which  you  can  disregard  when  it 
becomes  inconvenient  is  perhaps  only  a  prejudice. 

(1)  Mr.  Eussell  admits  that  we  know  the  existence  of 
other  minds.  Now  other  minds,  on  his  view,  are  groups  of 
sensations  lying  wholly  beyond  those  that  compose  our 
minds.  They  are  thus  exactly  in  the  position  which  I  have 
suggested  for  the  sub-sensations  constituting  physical  objects. 
Yet  he  holds  that  they  can  be  known.  It  is  true  that  they 
are  known,  in  his  opinion,  by  inference ;  that  he  does  not 
attribute  to  the  inference  complete  logical  rigour ;  and  that 
he  generously  helps  it  out  with  a  dose  of  irresistible  belief. 
Now  I  do  not  understand  the  status  of  such  belief  in  a 
phenomenalistic  philosophy.  I  should  argue,  either  that  the 
belief  was  unjustified  (and  Mr.  Eussell  does  seem  to  retain 
it  with  a  certain  apologetic  air),  or  that  the  philosophy  was 
false. 

('2)  Mr.  Eussell's  account  of  memory  represents  a  complete 
departure  from  the  phenomenalistic  principle.  If  he  were 
to  follow  here  the  pattern  set  by  his  account  of  perception, 
he  would  say  that  when  we  remember  an  event  on  a  number 
of  later  occasions,  as  we  often  do,  what  is  present  to  our 
minds  is  a  series  of  images — or  '  retrospectives,'  as  we  might 
call  them ;  that  the  past  event  is  the  temporal  limit  of  these 
'  retrospectives/  a  mere  mental  construction  ;  and  that  to 


314  c.  A.  STRONG: 

suppose  it  was  anything  more,  or  ever  really  happened,  in- 
volves the  fallacy  of  things  in  themselves.  Instead  of  this, 
he  admits  that  the  past  experience  or  sensation  lies  wholly 
beyond  the  present  memory-image,  and  can  yet  be  known 
by  means  of  it.  What  is  more,  he  does  not  regard  the 
knowledge  as  inferential,  but  as  direct.  But,  if  a  present 
image  can  give  knowledge  of  a  past  sensation,  why  cannot  a 
present  sensation  give  knowledge  of  a  present  or  just  preced- 
ing sub-sensation  ? 

(3)  Mr.  Kussell  holds,  I  think  I  may  say,  that  physical 
things  are  known  to  exist  when  they  are  no  longer  seen  or 
touched.  Is  such  knowledge  really  consistent  with  the 
phenomenalistic  principle?  He  will  again  be  obliged  to  eke 
out  his  logic  with  irresistible  belief.  For  how  is  it  possible 
that  perception,  which  by  its  nature  can  only  inform  us  of 
the  existence  of  objects  while  we  perceive  them,  should  give 
us  the  slightest  logical  ground  for  inferring  their  existence 
when  they  are  not  perceived  ?  Their  reappearance  is  110 
proof  ;  for  it  might  be  a  re-creation.  But  if,  when  we  see 
or  touch  them,  the  visual  or  tactile  appearance  is  accompanied 
by  a  belief  that  something  having  those  characters  exists, 
then  it  is  natural  that  its  existence,  which  is  independent  of 
its  appearing,  should  continue  when  the  appearance  ceases. 
Thus  the  continued  existence  of  objects  follows  intelligibly 
from  anti-phenomenalism,  but  not  from  phenomenalism. 

Mr.  Russell  believes,  as  we  have  seen,  that  the  perspectives 
which  are  not  appearances  to  human  beings  or  animals  are 
quite  unlike  those  which  are ;  and  I  have  given  a  reason 
for  thinking  that  they  are  not  even  perspectives.  If  so, 
sub -sensations  behind  the  visual  appearance  could  hardly  be 
more  unlike  it  than  these  sub-sensations  beside  it.  And 
they  have  the  advantage  that  an  act  of  cognition  (cognition 
as  I  have  above  analysed  it)  is  directly  brought  to  bear  upon 
them :  so  that  we  have  means  of  knowing  their  existence. 
That  the  substance  of  things — though  still  of  the  nature  of 
sensation — must  be  somewhat  unlike  their  appearances,  is 
evident  from  the  fact  that  the  visual  and  tactile  appearances 
are  unlike.  Now  we  cannot  suppose  that  objects  persist  in 
the  two  separate  forms  of  perspectives  and,  so  to  say,  con- 
tacts— that  the  same  object  consists,  when  unperceived,  of 
these  two  different  kinds  of  sub-sensations :  on  the  contrary, 
there  must  be  but  one  kind  of  sub-sensations,  and  the 
difference  between  visual  and  tactile  appearances  must  be 
relative  to  us. 

What  is  even  more  important,  we  cannot  suppose  that 
there  are  two  different  kinds  of  space  existing  externally, 


ME.  RUSSELL'S  THEORY  OF  THE  EXTERNAL  WORLD.    315- 

one  visual  and  the  other  tactile,  but  must  assume  that  the 
space  we  see  is  the  same  space  as  that  which  we  touch. 
We  thus  reaffirm  what  is,  to  my  mind,  the  most  vital  tenet, 
of  common  sense — the  unity  and  continuity  of  space.  And 
the  same  argument  leads  us  to  the  unity  and  continuity  of 
time.  I  cannot  get  over  my  surprise  at  Mr.  Eussell's  sin- 
gular contentment  with  a  world  that  is  discontinuous. 

Now  let  us  compare  the  metaphysics  I  have  sketched  with- 
his  metaphysics,  from  the  point  of  view  of  economy  of 
thought.  At  first  sight  his  system  might  seem  to  be  the 
simpler — since  he  assumes  only  appearances,  while  I  assume 
appearances  and  things  that  appear.  (My  appearances,  as 
I  have  said  and  shall  soon  explain  at  greater  length,  are  only 
sensations  in  so  far  as  they  are  used  as  signs.)  But  Mr. 
Eussell  assumes  for  each  object  an  infinite  number  of  per- 
spectives, all  of  which  are  actual ;  and  as  the  world  contains 
(we  may  say)  an  infinite  number  of  objects,  that  makes  the- 
total  number  of  actual  perspectives  infinitely  infinite. 
Whereas,  on  my  theory,  the  only  actual  perspectives  are 
those  which  appear  to  some  man  or  animal,  all  the  others 
being  merely  possible;  and,  apart  from  perspectives,  what 
exists  is  simply  the  sub-sensations  constituting  the  object. 
If  entia  non  sunt  multiplicand  a  praeter  necessitatem,  as  Mr. 
Eussell  insists,  it  seems  to  me  that  my  theory  has  the  advan- 
tage. 

III. 

I  have  now  dealt  pretty  completely  with  Mr.  Eussell's- 
theory  so  far  as  it  concerns  the  relation  between  appearances 
and  objects ;  and  I  turn  to  the  relation  between  appear- 
ances and  sensations.  I  believe  that,  as  he  fails  to  make  a> 
necessary  distinction,  or  at  least  fails  to  conceive  correctly 
the  distinction,  between  appearances  and  the  things  that 
appear,  so  he  fails  to  make  a  necessary  distinction  between, 
appearances  and  the  sensations  which  convey  them  ;  and 
that  the  whole  situation  becomes  very  much  clearer  when 
this  distinction  is  properly  made. 

I  say  he  does  not  make  it ;  but,  in  point  of  fact,  he  has 
made  it,  though  not,  I  think,  with  all  the  desirable  clearness, 
in  his  analysis  of  memory.  After  explaining  that  a  memory 
consists  of  an  image,  accompanied  by  a  belief,  to  the  effect 
that  '  this  occurred,7  he  says  that  of  course  the  '  this  '  does 
not  refer  to  the  image  as  a  present  existence ;  and  adds  that 
the  belief  confers  upon  the  image  something  called  '  mean- 
ing'. Now  I  do  not  wish  to  be  over-critical,  and  urge  that 


316  c.  A.  STRONG: 

the  'meaning,'  being  that  which  is  believed,  is  at  least  logi- 
cally prior  to  the  belief,  and  presumably  is  not  conferred  on 
the  image  by  the  belief  but  by  some  other  mental  function. 
Let  it  suffice  that  Mr.  Kussell  has  here  explicitly  recognised 
that  cognition,  at  any  rate  in  the  case  of  memory,  involves  a 
category  which  is  distinct  from  the  image  as  a  present 
mental  state,  without  being  on  that  account  identical  with 
the  object.  And  what  I  shall  now  try  to  show  is  that  a 
similar  distinction  requires  to  be  made  in  the  case  of  sensa- 
tion. 

When,  for  instance,  an  outer  object  acts  on  the  body  and 
calls  forth  a  visual  sensation,  that  is  not  the  whole  account 
of  what  happens :  for  (at  least  if  the  object  is  to  be  one  dis- 
tinctly perceived)  we  turn  our  attention,  i.e.,  fix  our  gaze,  in 
the  direction  of  the  object,  and  accommodate  th  e  eye-muscles 
to  it  in  such  a  way  that  it  is  seen  as  at  a  certain  distance. 
Sensation  and  motion,  in  other  words,  converge  upon  the 
object,  and  the  datum  of  vision  is  not  simply  the  sensation, 
but  the  sensation  as  referred  to  that  spot — it  is  not  the  sen- 
sation as  an  existence,  but  the  '  meaning '  which  the  sensa- 
tion conveys.  Suppose  the  thing  I  look  at  is  a  grate-fire : 
the  datum  is  not  the  mere  quality  light,  but  something 
luminous  situated  at  a  certain  distance.  And  if  at  the  same 
time  I  hold  out  my  hands,  there  are  not  two  data,  the  heat 
and  the  light,  but  one,  a  hot  and  luminous  thing,  a  grate-fire. 
There  are  not  two  spaces  given,  one  that  I  see,  and  one  in 
which  I  hold  out  my  hands,  but  the  one  space  in  which  the 
grate- fire  appears  at  a  certain  point.  In  short,  the  datum  is 
not  restricted  to  one  sense,  but  is  the  datum  of  all  the  senses 
that  are  brought  to  bear  upon  the  object ;  and  it  is  not  in 
its  nature  really  a  sensible  thing,  but  something  grasped  by 
means  of  sense,  something  understood  or  '  meant '. 

To  this  it  may  be  objected  that  what  is  meant  is  the  object 
itself.  What  need  of  erecting  an  intermediate  category  be- 
tween the  sensation  which  means  and  the  object  which  is 
meant?  The  answer  is  that  we  sometimes  mean,  in  this 
sensible  way,  objects  that  do  not  exist — as  in  the  hallucina- 
tions of  the  insane,  or  in  dreaming — and  that  a  distinction 
"has  to  be  made  between  these  dream  objects,  which  are  un- 
real, and  yet  present  to  the  mind,  and  the  sensations  convey- 
ing them,  which  are  real.  It  follows  that,  even  in  normal 
perception,  the  appearance  presented  by  the  use  of  a  sensation 
in  order  to  mean  an  object  is  not  the  object  itself  ;  but  is  only 
its  presentment  to  a  mind. 

But  an  opposite  objection  may  be  made.  What  we  have 
called  data  of  sensation  may  be  admitted,  but  it  may  be 


ME.  EUSSELL'S  THEOEY  OF  THE  EXTEENAL  WOELD.    817" 

denied  that  there  are  any  sensations,  distinct  from  the  data. 
Mr.  Russell,  on  the  whole,  means  by  '  sensations '  the  data  ; 
he  speaks  of  sensations  and  of  appearances  interchangeably. 
But  surely  you  can,  after  looking  at  a  grate-fire,  turn  your 
attention  to  the  mere  sensation  of  light,  a  thing  that  is  a 
state  of  yourself  in  the  same  way  that  a  pain  is ;  or  to  the 
mere  sensation  of  heat,  which  a  moment  ago  was  felt  to  be 
the  heat  of  the  fire.  You  can  use  these  feelings  as  media  of 
cognition,  or  you  can  consider  them  in  themselves,  and  in  the 
latter  case  what  you  consider  is  not  a  mere  detached  quality  of 
the  fire,  for  it  is  now  recognised  to  be  a  state  of  yourself.  In 
my  opinion,  such  states  constitute  the  ego,  or  at  least  the 
particular  part  of  it  that  perceives.  Such  a  state  was  what 
enabled  the  ego  to  remember.  Either  sensations,  distinct 
from  the  appearances,  must  be  admitted  in  perception,  or 
else  no  present  mental  image  can  exist  in  memory. 

Mr.  Eussell  no  longer  believes  in  an  '  act,'  by  which  the 
appearance  is  apprehended ;  this  is  perhaps  the  most  import- 
ant change  in  his  views  announced  in  this  book.  If  by  *  act ' 
he  means  a  diaphanous  awareness  contemplating  the  appear- 
ance, or  the  deed  of  a  punctiform  ego  that  has  the  awareness, 
the  change  is  to  be  applauded ;  for  neither  of  these  things  is 
really  observable.  But  things  having  the  same  functional 
relations  reappear  on  the  sensationalistic  theory.  For,  if  we 
admit  that  the  object  was  perceived  by  the  use  of  the  sensa- 
tion as  a  sign,  then  the  sensation,  being  a  state  of  the  self, 
occupies  the  position  of  ego,  and  its  use  as  a  sign  is  the  act 
of  awareness.  Mr.  Russell  holds  that  sensations,  considered 
in  themselves,  are  not  cognitive.  Quite  so :  they  are  cog- 
nitive only  so  far  as  they  are  used  as  signs. 

The  great  defect  of  most  thinking  on  the  subject  of  per- 
ception is  that,  at  the  very  outset,  the  sensations  (e.g.,  of  light 
and  heat,  in  the  case  of  the  grate-fire)  are  substituted  for  the 
true  datum,  the  appearance — the  object  of  introspection  for 
the  appearance  in  perception.  Or,  say,  the  two  are  confused, 
and  treated  as  one,  and  statements  are  made  of  the  fused 
product  which  really  apply,  now  to  the  appearance,  now  to- 
the  sensation.  It  is  as  if,  in  the  case  of  memory,  the  image 
were  treated  as  of  course  that  which  is  present  to  the  mind,, 
as  the  primary  datum,  out  of  which  by  some  subsequent 
process  a  memory  is  evolved.  Whereas  in  truth  we  do  not 
think  of  the  image  at  all,  but  what  is  before  our  minds  is 
the  vision  of  the  past.  It  is  only  by  turning  our  attention 
away  from  this  vision  to  the  present  state  of  the  self  which- 
it  involves  that  we  become  aware  of  the  image. 

I  will  illustrate  this  distinction  by  one  more  example.     The; 


'318  c.  A.  STEONG: 

perspectives  which  play  so  large  a  part  in  Mr.  Eussell's 
theory  are,  I  think,  in  his  conception  tridimensional;  and 
there  can  be  no  question  that  the  datum  of  vision  includes 
three  dimensions.  But,  when  we  look  into  the  matter,  we 
find  that  depth  is  not  given  in  quite  the  same  manner  that 
length  and  breadth  are — it  is  not  strictly  visual,  it  cannot  be 
found  in  the  visual  field  as  a  colour  can,  but  is  a  feature  of 
the  datum  brought  before  us  by  means  of  sensations  in  the 
muscles  of  accommodation  and  convergence.  Thus  all  that 
is  strictly  visual  is  a  coloured  field  in  two  dimensions.  Mr. 
Russell  is  not  right,  then,  when  he  speaks  of  the  perspectives 
as  sensations ;  they  are  appearances,  and  the  sensations  are 
the  visual  and  muscular  feelings  that  enable  us  to  see  them. 

Nothing  therefore  could  be  further  from  the  truth  than 
the  view  that  our  visual  sensations  are  a  part  of  the  object. 
They  are  in  their  nature  impressions  on  us,  produced  by  its 
action  on  our  bodies,  and  when  used  as  signs  they  enable  us 
to  see  the  object,  bnt  they  are  not  even  then  a  part  of  it. 
They  are  only  visions  of  it,  and  as  unsubstantial  as  visions 
proverbially  are. 

It  will  now  be  intelligible  how  I  could  maintain  that  ap- 
pearances are  not  existences.  The  only  existences  are,  in 
perception,  the  sub-sensations  constituting  the  object  and  the 
sensations  that  enable  us  to  perceive  it;  in  memory,  the 
sensation  remembered  and  the  image  by  means  of  which  we 
remember  it.  The  world  consists  entirely  of  sensations  and 
sub-sensations  (the  former  being,  of  course,  a  development  out 
of  the  latter)  arranged  in  space  and  time. 

This  distinction  permits  us  to  bring  order  into  the  perplexed 
question  of  causal  relations  in  cognition.  It  is  felt  that  the 
object  cannot  be  the  cause  of  the  appearance ;  because  the 
appearance  is  the  revelation  of  the  object,  and  thus  bears  an 
entirely  different  relation  to  it.  And  yet  it  is  undeniable 
that  perception  is  called  forth  by  the  action  of  the  object  on 
the  body.  Indeed,  the  eye  is  an  organ  specially  evolved  to 
produce  a  sensation,  the  parts  of  which  have  the  same 
spatial  arrangement  as  the  parts  of  the  object.  Everything 
becomes  clear  if  we  consider  that  what  the  object  calls  forth 
is  only  the  sensation,  and  that  the  appearance  is  due  to  the 
'  intentional '  use  of  the  sensation  as  a  sign  of  the  object.  In 
the  same  way,  a  past  sensation  leaves  behind  an  image,  the 
relation  between  the  two  being  causal,  but  the  vision  of 
the  past  is  not  the  image  itself  but  its  intentional  use  for 
the  past  sensation. 

The  terms  I  have  thus  far  used,  'appearance'  and  'meaning,' 
are  extrinsic  designations,  marking  the  thing  referred  to  by 


MR.  RUSSELL'S  THEORY  OF  THE  EXTERNAL  WORLD.    319 

the  fact  that  it  appears  to  some  one,  or  that  some  one  means 
or  thinks  of  it ;  but,  considered  in  itself,  this  thing  is  an 
'  essence ' — that  is,  an  entity  having  the  kind  of  being  that 
anything  must  have  in  order  that  you  may  think  of  it.  An 
essence  is  thus  the  entire  concrete  nature  of  a  thing,  in 
abstraction  from  its  existence.  It  is  easy  to  show  that,  if 
there  is  to  be  knowledge  at  all,  it  must  be  by  means  of 
essences. 

I  assume  that  the  world  is  continuous  in  space  and  in 
time,  that  its  parts  are  separately  existent,  and  that  it  has 
no  greater  unity  than  this  continuity.  Now  an  animal  that 
knows  is  confined  in  his  existence  to  a  certain  place  and  a 
certain  time.  How  then  is  he  to  know  things  in  other 
places  and  at  other  times,  whose  existence  is  separate  from 
his  own — things,  indeed,  separated  from  him  by  the  entire 
intervening  distance  or  lapse  of  time,  or  both?  One  hy- 
pothesis is  that  his  existence  goes  out  to  them,  by  a  mysterious 
act  of  intuition.  But  this  is  contradicted  by  the  fact  that 
cognition  rests  on  causality.  Another  hypothesis  is  that 
their  existence  obligingly  comes  to  him — as  in  M.  Bergson's 
theory  that  the  past  still  exists  in  the  present,  or  in  Mr. 
Russell's  theory  that  my  visual  sensations  are  an  actual  part 
of  the  star  I  see.  In  reality  these  views  contradict  the 
nature  of  space  and  time — since  the  past  is  what  no  longer 
exists,  and  yet  M.  Bergson  says  that  it  still  exists ;  since  the 
star  is  at  a  great  distance  from  me,  and  yet  Mr.  Russell  says 
that  it  is  a  part  of  me. 

The  utmost  that  cognition  can  do  is  to  show  me  an  essence , 
ivhich  is  the  essence  of  the  object,  and  to  lead  me  to  act  as  if 
that  essence  were  real,  at  the  place  or  time  indicated  by  my 
action. 

I  will  not  elaborate  this  theory,  for  it  seems  to  me  to 
follow  so  necessarily  from  what  has  gone  before  that  the 
demonstration  is  now  complete. 

To  sum  up,  Mr.  Russell  has  given  us  a  theory  of  the  ex- 
ternal world  based  on  the  phenomenalistic  principle,  and  has 
worked  it  out  with  the  greatest  ingenuity.  With  that  keen 
logical  zest  which  characterises  him,  he  has  shown  that  a 
complete  science  of  physics  can  be  constructed  simply  upon 
the  basis  of  appearances,  without  the  assumption  of  anything 
that  appears.  But  this  achievement  has  the  same  value  as 
that  of  a  psychologist  who  should  show  that  a  complete 
science  of  the  human  mind  can  be  constructed  simply 
upon  the  basis  of  observations  of  human  behaviour,  without 
the  assumption  of  any  thoughts  or  feelings  behind  that 


320  ME.-  EUSSELL'S  THEOEY  OF  THE  EXTEENAL  WOELD. 

behaviour.  Such  a  psychologist  might  believe  himself  to  be 
proceeding  according  to  the  only  truly  scientific  method,  and 
he  might  draw  his  conclusions  with  exemplary  logical  rigour ; 
but  his  conception  of  the  object  of  his  science  would  be  a 
mistaken  one,  because  pure  phenomenalism  as  applied  to  the 
human  body  is  false.  I  would  ask  Mr.  Eussell,  and  those 
who  are  tempted  to  agree  with  him,  to  consider  whether 
phenomenalism  as  applied  to  other  objects  than  the  human 
body  is  not  also  false. 


IV.— VISUAL  IMAGES,  WORDS  AND  DREAMS. 

BY  JOSHUA  C.  GEEGOEY. 

HOMEE  compared  the  swift  flight  of  Hera  to  the  dart  of 
thought  in  a  travelled  man  who,  touched  by  some  incident 
to  rapid  recollection,  swiftly  inspects,  in  memory,  scenes 
from  his  past  life  "and  considers  in  his  wise  heart,  'would 
that  I  were  here  or  there '  ".l  Such  pictures  of  the  past, 
either  recollected  as  occurrences  or  imaginatively  surveyed 
without  reminiscence,  are  familiar  experiences.  Visual 
mental  images  which  reproduce  past  experiences  as  they 
were  SEEN  may  flash  upon  the  mind  in  panoramic  spread,  as 
they  flashed  upon  Homer's  travelled  man,  or  they  may  be 
casual,  and  perhaps  vaguely  incomplete,  mental  pictures. 
Bertrand  Eussell  probably  thought  of  this  milder  visualisa- 
tion as  he  wrote:  "When  you  hear  New  York  spoken  of, 
some  image  probably  comes  into  your  mind,  either  of  the 
place  itself  (if  you  have  been  there),  or  of  some  picture  of  it 
(if  you  have  not)  ".2  Homer's  comparison  of  Hera's  swift- 
ness to  the  rapidity  of  panoramic  recollection  declares  his 
familiarity  with  the  visual  mental  images  of  memory  and 
imagination.  He  would  have  stared  at  Watson's  proposal  to 
"throw  out  imagery  altogether"  from  psychology  and  have 
assented  to  Bertrand  Kussell's  comment :  "If  you  try  to 
persuade  any  uneducated  person  that  she  cannot  call  up  a 
visual  picture  of  a  friend  sitting  in  a  chair,  but  can  only  use 
words  describing  what  such  an  occurrence  would  be  like,  she 
will  conclude  that  you  are  mad".3  Homer's  surprise  is 
significant ;  for  Watson  is  probably  eager  to  jettison  visual 
images  because  he  is  not  favoured  with  them.  It  is  signi- 
ficant because  visual  memory  and  imagination  seem  to  vary 
in  degree  and  extent  from  those  for  whom  recollection  is 
essentially  a  visualised  panorama  to  those  for  whom  it  is 
quite  devoid  of  visual  images.  "Visual  image,"  or  "  mental 
picture,"  need  only  be  used  descriptively  in  the  present  con- 
nexion to  describe  an  experience  which  is  familiar  to  most, 
though  not  to  all.  Homer's  reminiscent  travelled  man, 
Alexander  believes,  interviewed  the  actual  scenes  which  he 

1  IL  15,  82.     (Trans.  Lang,  Leaf  and  Myers.) 

2  The  Analysis  of  Mind,  p.  80.  3  Loc  cit.,  p.  153. 

21 


322  JOSHUA  c.  GREGORY: 

had  formerly  interviewed  in  perception,  though  he  inter- 
viewed them  under  the  circumstances  known  as  remember- 
ing :  images  are  not  pictures  in  the  mind  as  we  naturally,  and 
no  doubt  in  ordinary  life  very  conveniently,  think,  but  things 
themselves  interviewed  under  the  particular  circumstances 
known  as  memory,  expectation  or  imagination.1  Occasional 
individuals  are  never  tempted  by  their  experiences  to  speak 
of  "  visual  images  "  because  they  never  experience  any,  but 
most  people,  probably  in  this  respect  resembling  Homer  more 
than  Watson,  when  they  think,  for  example,  of  their  summer 
bathing,  can  see,  in  their  mind's  eye,  the  tent  from  which 
they  bathed.  This  reminiscent  visualisation  of  the  past, 
however  achieved  and  whatever  be  its  real  nature,  can  be 
described  as  mental  visual  imagery  without  prejudice  to  the 
ultimate  status  ascribed  by  Alexander  to  the  image  and,  in 
the  present  connexion,  considered  as  mental  imagery  which 
mimics  the  visual  aspects  of  seen  things,  as  a  reflexion  in 
the  water  mimics  a  tree  by  the  brink  of  a  pool. 
.  To  those  who  experience  them  visual  images  are  as  familiar 
in  imagination  without  any  tinge  of  reminiscence  as  they 
are  in  recollection.  Titchener  mingles  ''visual  hints"  into 
his  thinking  :  when  he  thinks  of  "  modesty  "  he  sees  a  grace- 
ful, bending  female  figure  and  when  he  thinks  of  "  the  pro- 
gress of  science "  he  sees  the  inflowing  tide.2  This  is 
intelligible  to  people  who  mingle  visual  images  much  less 
freely  into  their  thinking  than  he,  and  they,  in  company  with 
others  who  visualise  more  freely  even  than  Titchener,  under- 
stand Socrates'  remark  to  Simmias  that  lovers,  when  they 
recognise  a  lyre,  "  form  in  the  mind's  eye  an  image  of  the 
youth  to  whom  the  lyre  belongs,"3  and  Hamlet's  reply  "In 
my  mind's  eye,  Horatio  ".4  There  are  experiences  in  which 
the  mind  seems  to  have  an  eye  and  things  happen  as  if 
visual  images  were  in  this  eye,  as  the  reflected  images  of 
physical  things  are  in  the  physical  eye.  Behaviouristic  dis- 
claimers and  visualistic  deprivations  cannot  negate  the 
common  experience  in  which  things  happen  as  if  mental 
images  mimic  the  visual  aspects  of  seen  things  when  these 
things  are  out  of  perceptive  range.  Nor  can  they  success- 
fully deny  that  the  dreamer  thinks  absent  things  are  present 
as  if  there  were  visual  images  in  his  mind  which  he  mistakes 
for  outward  objects — as  he  might  mistake  a  mirage  in  the 
desert  for  a  real  oasis.  Such  visual  images,  descriptively 

1  Space,  Time  and  Deity,  i.,  25  ;  ii.,  218. 

^Lectures  on  the   Experimental  Psychology  of  the  Thought  Processes, 
ch.  i. 

3  Phaedo  (Jowefct's  Trans.).  4 Hamlet,  L,  ii.,  186. 


VISUAL   IMAGES,   WOEDS  AND  DEEAMS.  323 

described  as  such  to  avoid  conflict  with  realistic  inter- 
pretations of  their  real  status,  seem  to  have  an  interesting 
connexion  with  dreaming  which  the  present  article  proposes 
to  discuss. 

Visual  images  can  inflict  damage  on  the  mind  and  its 
thinking.  Association  can  play  scurvy  tricks  even  on  grave 
philosophers  :  "  The  celebrated  Descartes  was  very  much  in 
love  with  a  lady  who  squinted ;  he  had  so  associated  that 
passion  with  obliquity  of  vision,  that  he  declared  to  the  latest 
hour  of  his  life  he  could  never  see  a  lady  with  a  cast  in  her 
eyes,  without  experiencing  the  most  lively  emotions".1 
Descartes  suffered  periodically  from  an  insistent  emotion ; 
Easselas,  during  his  broodings,  suffered  from  insistent  images. 
"  One  day,  as  he  was  sitting  on  a  bank,  he  feigned  to  himself 
an  orphan  virgin  robbed  of  her  little  portion  by  a  treacherous 
lover,  and  crying  after  him  for  restitution.  So  strongly  was 
the  image  impressed  upon  his  mind  that  he  started  up  in  the 
maid's  defence  and  ran  forward  to  seize  the  plunderer  with 
all  the  eagerness  of  a  real  pursuit."^  Great  writers  freely 
depict  their  characters  under  siege  by  insistent  images. 
When  Crusoe  had  left  his  island  and  been  ill,  his  "imagina- 
tion worked  up  to  such  a  height  "  that  he  SAW  the  "  old 
Spaniard,  Friday's  father,  and  the  reprobate  sailors,"  "  looked 
at  them  steadily  ...  as  at  persons  just  before  "  him  and 
often  frightened  himself  with  "  the  images "  of  his  fancy. 
Don  Quixote's  mind  became  "  a  world  of  disorderly  notions" 
and  a  chaos  of  turbulent  images  made  him  insane.  Noth- 
ing is  proved  by  making  events  happen  in  a  story ;  but  these 
fictions  are  felt  to  be  essentially  unfictitious  because  imagina- 
tion can,  and  does,  do  violence  to  the  mind. 

Darwin  cites  the  hallucination  of  a  gentleman  who,  after 
looking  attentively  at  a  small  statue  of  the  Virgin,  raised  his 
head  and  saw  the  same  appearance  at  the  end  of  the  room.3 
This  milder  type  of  siege  does  not  menace  sanity  as  the 
fiercer  sieges,  like  those  of  Crusoe  and  Don  Quixote,  menace 
it,  but  the  insistent  image  always  tends  to  damage  thought 
by  detaining  attention  upon  itself.  Titchener  wrote  of  the 
"visual  hints"  which  mingle  in  his  thinking,  and  images 
more  properly  subserve  thought  by  unobtrusiveness  than  by 
insistence.  "  Any  such  narrative  will  present  to  me  some 
image,"  writes  Max  Beerbohm,  "  and  stir  me  to  not  altogether 
fatuous  thought."4  He  perceives  the  essential  function  of 


1  Sydney  Smith,  Elementary  Sketches  of  Moral  Philosophy,  p.  297. 

2  Rasselas,  ch.  iv.  :!  Taine,  de  L' Intelligence,  ii.,  ch.  i. 
4  "  And  Even  Now  :  Servants." 


324  JOSHUA  c.  GEEGOEY: 

the  visual  image  in  thinking.  Turbulent,  crowding  images 
stir  the  mind  too  violently  and  shake  it  rather  than  guide  it. 
Images  which  are  simply  too  insistent  do  not  stir  it  enough 
—do  not  pass  on  the  mind  freely  enough  because  they  invite 
its  attention  to  cling  to  themselves. 

Great  visualising  power  can  confer  benefit.  Calculating 
prodigies  have  said  that  they  saw  their  figures  clearly  before 
them  as  though  they  were  written  on  a  slate.1  In  calculating 
or  blindfold  chess-playing  it  is  an  obvious  advantage  to  have 
a  mental  slate  or  chess-board.  The  intensification  of  his 
images  secured  for  him  by  his  emotion  must  assist  the  painter 
to  represent  those  pictorial  aspects  of  things  which  arouse 
that  emotion  within  him.2  Hogarth  aimed  at  the  nurture 
of  visualisation:  "I  had  one  material  advantage  over  my 
competitors,  viz.,  the  early  habit  I  thus  acquired  of  retain- 
ing in  my  mind's  eye,  without  coldly  copying  it  on  the  spot, 
whatever  I  intended  to  imitate".3  Sir  Joshua  Keynolds 
pointed  the  painter  to  the  value  of  the  mental  image  :  "  When- 
ever a  story  is  related,  every  man  forms  a  picture  in  his  mind 
of  the  action  and  expression  of  the  persons  employed.  The 
power  of  representing  this  mental  picture  on  canvas  is  what 
we  call  invention  in  a  painter."  4  A  descent  from  art  to  stage 
clairvoyancy  or  telepathy  lights  upon  another  helpfulness  in 
vivid  visualising  power.  Eobert  Houdin  chose  an  object  at 
random  from  one  of  the  audience,  and  his  blindfolded  son,  at 
a  conventional  sign  from  his  father,  simulated  second  sight 
and  described  the  object.  The  Houdins  had,  apparently,  in 
their  conventional  signs  a  code  of  cues  ;  but  their  performance 
depended  essentially  on  young  Houdin's  training  in  visualisa- 
tion. His  father  taught  him  to  take  "  mental  photographs" 
of  the  people  in  the  audience  and  of  the  objects  on  their 
persons.  Mental  photographs  plus  judicious  cueing  thus 
provided  an  ingenious  simulation  of  telepathy.5  Whenever, 
to  sum  up  shortly,  it  is  an  advantage  to  see  objects  without 
looking  at  them  it  is  an  advantage  to  have  vigorous  and 
abundant  visual  images. 

But  the  "  stir  "  referred  to  by  Max  Beerbohm  contemplates 
an  activity  of  thought  distinct  from  mere  picturing  of  objects. 
Titchener's  imagery  is  relatively  scattered  and  is  largely  a 
disintegrated  remnant  of  complete  mental  pictures.  This 
scattering  and  disintegration  is  still  more  marked  in  many 
minds,  and  visualisation  is  obviously  reduced  to  a  provision  of 

1  Taine,  de  L' Intelligence,  ii.,  ch.  i. 

2  Holmes,  Notes  on  the  Science  of  Picture-Making,  pp.  15-16. 

3  Austin  Dobson,  William  Hogarth,  p.  15.  4  Fourth  Discourse- 
8  Bergson,  Mind-Energy  (Can's  Trans.),  pp.  156-157. 


VISUAL   IMAGES,   WOEDS  AND  DBEAMS.  325 

cues  for  thinking.  The  visual  image  proper  can  be  completely 
replaced  by  the  mental  picture  of  a  word  which  is  a  mere 
symbol  of  the  object  with  no  resemblance  to  it.  Words  are 
heard  as  well  as  seen  and  also  experienced  as  articulatory 
movements  but  visual  aspects  alone  are  under  discussion 
here.  Since  seen  or  visualised  words  can  serve  thought  and 
"stir"  it,  efficiently  replacing  sight  or  mental  mimicry  of 
sight,  visual  images  have  obviously  the  important  function 
of  inciting  or  promoting  thought.  If  visualisation  is  too 
vigorous,  if  mental  images  insistently  claim  attention,  thought 
suffers  a  paralysis  which  may  be  compared  to  the  too  hard 
stare  at  an  object  which  permits  no  real  play  to  thought. 

The  human  mind  has  shown  a  marked  tendency  to  abandon 
the  advantage  of  seeing  things  without  looking  at  the,m,  con- 
ferred by  the  power  of  vigorous  visualisation,  for  the  advan- 
tage of  thinking  about  them  conferred  by  feebler  mental 
images  which  direct  the  mind  to  thought  rather  than  to 
themselves.  When  Eoger  Fry  says  of  the  Bushmen  that 
they  seem  to  have  retained  the  palaeolithic  "  unique  power  of 
visual  transcription"  and  of  the  lowest  savages  that  they 
show  "  this  peculiar  power  of  visualisation  "  he  expresses  a 
very  common  belief  in  the  superiority  of  uncivilised  over 
civilised  men  in  visualising  power.1  W.  H.  Hudson  speaks 
of  a  revelation  "  in  swift  flickering  glimpses  "  of  "  a  vanished 
experience  or  state  of  the  primitive  mind — a  mind  undimmed 
by  speculation,  in  which  the  extraneous  world  is  vividly  re- 
flected ".2  Fry  deduces  from  relics  of  primitive  art,  and 
Hudson,  since  he  compares  the  animal  mind  to  the  visualistic 
mind  of  primitive  man,  is  evidently  speculative ;  but  direct 
observation  seems  to  support  this  combination  of  deduction 
and  speculation.  Rivers  says  of  an  old  woman  giving  evidence 
at  a  court  on  Murray  Island  that  "she  looked  first  in  one 
direction  and  then  in  another  with  a  keenness  and  directness 
which  showed  beyond  doubt  that  every  detail  of  the  occur- 
rences she  was  describing  was  being  enacted  before  her 
eyes  ".  The  demeanour  of  uncivilised  men  when  describing 
events  they  have  seen,  he  adds,  suggests  that  they  read  off 
memory  pictures  and  their  "exclusive  interest  in  the  con- 
crete," their  developed  powers  of  observation,  and  their  "  full- 
ness of  memory  of  the  more  concrete  events  of  their  lives  " 
intimate  that  "  imagery  is  especially  vivid  and  necessary 
among  primitive  peoples.  .  .  ."3  Carveth  Bead  echoes  a 
general  anthropological  estimate  when  he  writes :  "  The 

1  Vision  and  Design  :  The  Art  of  the  Bushmen. 

2  The  Book  of  a  Naturalist,  p.  19. 

3  Dreams  and  Primitive  Culture,  p.  11. 


326  JOSHUA  c.  GEEGOEY: 

process  of  imagination  itself,  the  memory  and  the  picture- 
thinking  of  savages,  seems  to  be  more  vivid,  sensuous,  stable, 
more  like  perception  than  our  own  normally  is".1 

The  depletion  of  visual  imagery  which  accompanies  the 
evolution  of  the  civilised  mind  seems  also  to  occur  in  the 
development  of  the  individual.  Young  children  of  five  or 
six,  according  to  Kimmins,  have  a  marked  VISUAL  appreciation 
of  the  stories  which  are  read  to  them.  This  visual  apprecia- 
tion prevents  them  from  relishing  many  well-known  comic 
stories  and  at  seven  years  there  is  a  transition  from  visual 
appreciation  to  an  elementary  play  upon  words.2  This  con- 
clusion has  a  weight  of  statistical  enquiry  behind  it  though 
it  may  seem  to  some  to  be  a  somewhat  speculative  interpreta- 
tion. A  "  correspondent "  considers  it  difficult  to  discover 
the  nature  of  the  images  in  a  child's  mind  but  thinks  that 
children  use  more  mental  pictures  for  thinking  than  adults.3 
This  opinion,  doubtless  based  on  many  observations  of  many 
children,  is  supported  by  the  personal  experience  of  Dr. 
Rivers.  His  mental  imagery  was  more  definite  in  youth, 
and  his  topographical  memory  of  the  houses  he  lived  in  is 
most  definite  for  the  house  he  left  at  five  years  old.4  The 
obvious  is  often  untrue  and  may  deceive  the  observer  about 
his  own  mind.  Familiarity  and  power  to  image  are  closely 
connected :  the  most  familiar  scenes  are,  normally,  most 
readily  depicted  in  the  mind.  Memories  of  childhood  which 
occur  often  and  continuously  in  reminiscence  can  be  seen 
vividly  because  they  are  familiar  and  we  may  mistake  our 
present  power  of  visualising  childhood  for  childhood's  power 
to  visualise.  But  when  Rivers  discovers  an  almost  complete 
absence  of  definite  visual  imagery  in  his  present  waking  life 
and  is  aware  of  more  definite  mental  imagery  when  he 
recollects  his  youth  it  becomes  probable  that  his  mental 
picturing  has  diminished  with  age. 

Eivers'  experience  adds  another  instance  to  Galton's  well- 
known  conclusion  that  visual  images  desert  the  scientific 
mind.  The  feeble  visualisation  attributed  by  Galton  to  men 
of  science  after  statistical  enquiry,  which  is  frequently  con- 
firmed by  direct  testimony,  as  by  Rivers,  or  by  indirect 
testimony,  as  by  Watson's  proposal  to  "  throw  out  imagery 
altogether,"  confirms  the  conclusion  drawn  from  the  devisual- 
ising  tendency  in  the  evolution  of  civilised  thought  and  in 
the  development  of  individual  minds  that  the  human  mind 

1  The  Origin  of  Man  and  of  his  Superstitions,  p.  88. 

2  Child  Study  Soc.,  13th  October,  1921 :  The  Springs  of  Laughter . 

3  Times'  Educ.  Supp.,  15th  Jan.,  1920:   What  is  Imagination? 

4  Instinct  and  the  Unconscious,  pp.  11-12. 


VISUAL   IMAGES,   WORDS  AND  DREAMS.  327 

tends  to  dispense  with  visual  images.  Titcheners  mingle 
"visual  hints"  into  their  thinking  and  Kekules,  pondering 
atomic  theories  on  London  buses,  see  atoms  dancing  in  mid- 
air1 to  destroy  the  perfection  of  Galton's  generalisations. 
But  Bertrand  Eussell  rightly  sees  "  no  reason  to  doubt  his 
conclusion  that  the  habit  of  abstract  pursuits  makes  learned 
men  much  inferior  to  the  average  in  power  of  visualising. 
.  .  ." 2  Thinking  may  become  less  occupied  with  the  visual 
image  because  it  becomes  more  preoccupied  with  words,  as 
seems  probable  and  as  Bertrand  Kussell  suggests,3  or  it  may 
shun  them  because,  as  Lord  Haldane  thinks,  "  the  metaphors 
that  arise  out  of  the  images  we  call  up,  even  in  the  strictest 
thought,  are  a  special  source  of  danger  in  scientific  and 
philosophic  investigation  ".4  Images  may  be  reserved  for 
art  because  they  are  there  essential,  and  dismissed  from 
scientific  description  because  there  "  the  power  of  imagina- 
tion has  to  be  kept  in  restraint  ".5  Depressed  visualisation 
may  be  good  or  bad,  desirable  or  deplorable,  submitted  to  or 
struggled  against ;  it  has  happened  in  mental  evolution  and 
it  happens  in  us.  Since  it  is  a  fact  of  experience  its 
mechanism  can  be  studied  and  that  study  is  a  duty  for 
psychology. 

Some  experiences  simultaneously  remind  us  of  the  depres- 
sion of  visual  images  and  hint  at  the  method  of  depression. 
The  "  correspondent "  who  discussed  children's  images  had 
a  friend  who  claimed  a  recovery  of  visualisation  by  reading 
slowly,  with  frequent  pauses  to  give  the  mental  pictures  time 
to  emerge.  The  writer's  experience  confirms  this  possibility. 
When  he  thinks  of  a  word,  the  word  "  horse  "  for  example, 
or  hears  it,  a  visual  image  of  the  word  itself  and  of  the  word 
only  rises  in  his  mind.  It  usually  flits  through  consciousness,, 
as  part  of  a  sentence,  bringing  significance  with  it,  as  a  waiter 
brings  a  plate  and  leaves.  If  he  detains  the  word  under 
attention,  pausing  to  observe  it,  images  of  horses  and  of  fields; 
or  carts  or  stables  or  of  other  items  connected  with  horses, 
appear  in  consciousness.  These  images  are  usually  excluded 
in  the  customary  conscious  flit  of  thinking  but  are  available. 
Restriction  of  imagery  thus  appears  as  a  customary  waiving 
of  a  right,  or  power,  which  can  still  be  exercised  on  occasion. 

The  visual  image  probably  developed  through  different 
stages  of  completeness 6  before  man  received  it  in  his  inherit- 
ance from  the  animal.  Visualisation  is  not  usually  described 

1  Knowlson,  Originality,  Sect.  2,  ch.  ii. 

2  The  Analysis  of  Mind,  p.  154. 

3  Ibid.  4  The  Reign  of  Relativity,  p.  220.  Ibid. 
6  Vide  Washburn,  The  Animal  Mind. 


328  JOSHUA  c.  GREGORY: 

as  an  instinct  but,  like  the  instincts,  it  is  a  strongly  marked 
pervasive  tendency  which  has  been  received  from  the  animals 
and  incorporated  into  the  general  habit  of  the  organism. 
Like  the  instincts  also  it  has  been  placed  under  control,  and 
like  the  instincts  it  has  its  moments  of  assertion  and  its 
periods  of  calm.  Images  may  invade  the  mind  as  the  impulse 
to  flight  may  invade  it  when  fear  arises  ;  and  they  may,  appar- 
ently, be  as  completely,  or  nearly  as  completely,  banished 
from  thought  as  flight  or  other  impulses  may  be  banished 
from  action.  If  images  or  mental  pictures  of  words  be  dis- 
tinguished from  other  visual  images  and  not  included,  as 
seems  to  be  a  very  usual  custom,  in  the  term  "  visual  image," 
the  tendency  to  visualise  is  often  very  completely  inhibited. 
Visualisation  can  be  regarded  as  a  tendency  to  mental  re- 
sponse by  visual  images  which  undergoes,  progressively  with 
the  evolution  of  civilisation  and  in  different  degrees  among 
the  minds  of  one  generation,  a  process  of  inhibition.  The 
mind  has  a  tendency  to  have  visual  images  when  it  thinks, 
and  an  inhibiting  mechanism  to  free  thought  from  them. 
The  inhibiting  mechanism  might  operate  in  one  of  two  ways. 
The  imaging  power  or  tendency  might  be  assimilated  into 
the  thinking  process  :  the  word  "  fairy,"  for  example,  instead 
of  stirring  pictures  of  these  dainty  beings  in  consciousness 
might  stir  in  it  a  general  sense  of  significance — the  mind 
realising  the  MEANING  of  the  word  without  illustrating  it  by 
visual  images.  Such  assimilation  might  l>e  compared  with 
nutrition  by  food  :  the  imaging  process  might  lose  its  identity 
in  the  total  process  of  thought  as  the  food  loses  its  identity 
in  the  metabolic  process. 

Such  inhibition,  if  the  term  "  inhibition "  is  admitted  to 
apply  to  such  assimilation,  is  a  virtual  destruction  of  the 
visualising  tendency  since  this  is  transformed  into  something 
else.  A  simple  loss  of  visualising  power,  which  would  make 
"  inhibition "  unnecessary,  would  have  exactly  the  same 
apparent  effect  of  clearing  images  out  of  consciousness.  It 
is,  however,  conceivable  that  "inhibition"  might  fail  at 
times  to  assimilate  the  visualising  tendency,  so  that  images 
get  into  consciousness.  The  virtual  destruction  of  the  visual- 
ising process  by  inhibition  is  thus  distinct  from  its  actual 
destruction,  since  the  original  tendency  to  imagery  may,  from 
time  to  time,  assert  itself.  If  some  people  have  practically 
no  visual  images1  their  visualising  tendencies  may  either  be 
destroyed  or  be  a  lingering  remnant  which  has  escaped  de- 
struction. The  showering  of  images  upon  the  mind  by 

1  James,  Principles  of  Psychology  :  Imagination. 


VISUAL   IMAGES,   WORDS  AND  DREAMS  329 

shock  favours  inhibition  of  visualisation  more  than  its  de- 
struction. De  Quincey  was  told  by  a  near  relative  who  fell 
into  a  river  and  was  just  saved  that  "  she  saw  in  a  moment 
her  whole  life,  clothed  in  its  forgotten  incidents,  arrayed  be- 
fore her  as  in  a  mirror".1  Some  Gold  Coast  natives  who 
had  been  almost  drowned  told  Cardinall  that  they  had  seen 
the  dwelling-places  of  water-spirits.2  They  had  doubtless 
had  visions  appropriate  to  their  minds,  as  De  Quincey's 
relative  had  visions  appropriate  to  her  mind,  which  had  been 
showered  upon  them  by  shock.  If,  as  seems  probable,  an 
apparently  completely  devisualised  mind  would  visualise 
under  shock,  devisualisation  probably  occurs  through  inhibi- 
tion, more  or  less  stringently  enforced. 

Since  the  inhibition  seems  often  and  in  many  respects  to 
be  but  lightly  enforced  (images  appearing,  for  example,  when 
the  reader  pauses  over  his  words)  visualisation  may  be 
normally  inhibited  merely  by  keeping  images  out  of  conscious- 
ness. This  is  the  second  possible  operation  of  the  inhibiting 
mechanism  and,  in  a  general  way,  it  corresponds  to  the 
"  suppression  "  of  instincts  suggested  by  Eivers,  as  assimil- 
atory  inhibition  corresponds  to  his  notion  of  "  fusion  ".3 
Devisualisation  may  proceed  inhibitorily  by  a  tendency  to 
make  visual  images  inaccessible  to  consciousness.  The  same 
process  may  also  be  expressed  as  an  inhibition  of  the  mental 
tendency  to  react  in  thinking  by  producing  images.  To 
secure  clearness  of  exposition  the  images  may  be  conceived 
to  sojourn  in  the  unconscious  ready  to  enter  consciousness 
and  devisualisation  to  be  an  inhibition  of  their  entry.  There 
are,  on  this  conception,  images  in  the  unconscious  mind, 
such  as  mental  pictures  of  horses  and  scenes  connected  with 
them,  ready  to  enter  consciousness  when,  for  instance,  the 
word  "horse"  is  seen  or  heard,  and  a  process  of  inhibition 
to  prevent  their  access.  This  inhibition  has  increased  in 
stringency  during  the  evolution  of  the  human  mind,  it  be- 
comes more  stringent  during  individual  development,  usually 
very  much  more  stringent  if  the  individual  inclines  to  scientific 
or  abstract  pursuits,  and  varies  in  stringency  among  the 
members  of  any  group — artists,  for  example,  inclining  to 
release  their  images  as  philosophers  incline  to  imprison 
them. 

Bivers  remarks  that  painful  experience  is  specially  liable 
to  "  suppression  ".4  By  such  "  suppression  "  any  experience 

1  Confessions  of  an  English  Opium-Eater,  Pfc.  3. 

2  The  Natives  of  the  Northern  Territory  of  the  Gold  Coast,  p.  34 

3  Instinct  and  the  Unconscious,  p.  33. 

4  Loc.  cit.,  p.  35. 


330  JOSHUA   C.    GKEGORY: 

is  rendered  inaccessible  to  consciousness,  but  special  con- 
ditions, such  as  dream  or  hypnotism,  may  restore  it  from 
the  unconscious  where  it  has  remained  active.  An  officer 
who  often  experienced  fear  when  he  was  enclosed  had  this- 
claustrophobia  greatly  intensified  at  the  fighting  front.  A 
painful  experience  in  an  enclosed  space  had  been  driven 
down  into  his  unconscious  to  trouble  his  conscious  life  when 
his  outward  surroundings  resembled  those  of  the  suppressed 
experience.  In  a  semi-waking  state  following  a  dream  he 
recalled  the  incident  which  had  remained  in  suppression  to- 
disturb  his  life.  At  the  age  of  four  he  had  been  in  the  blind 
end  of  a  passage  and  a  dog  had  followed  him  in  from  the  • 
open  end.  His  fear  of  the  animal  and  his  inability  to  escape 
had  sunk  into  his  mind  beyond  the  range  of  recollection  and 
the  suppressed  experience  remained  as  a  perpetual  suggestion 
of  menace  whenever  he  entered  an  enclosed  space.1  De- 
visualisation  probably  is  a  quieter  form  of  suppression  or 
inhibition,  which  restricts  the  access  of  images  to  conscious- 
ness. The  need  for  this  restriction  appears  in  some  instances 
where  vigorous  visualisation  would  seem  to  be  an  advantage. 
Taine  discovered  purely  visual  memories  in  chess-players  ; 
Binet  found  that  his  blindfolded  chess-players  were  disturbed 
by  mental  visions  of  their  pieces.  Binet's  subjects  recon- 
structed the  game  at  every  move  and  each  one  proceeded 
from  an  "idea  of  the  whole"  which  enabled  him,  if  he  so 
desired,  "to  visualise  the  elements".2  If  visualisation  can 
disturb  a  blindfolded  chess-player  who  would  apparently 
benefit  by  a  special  power  to  see  without  looking,  its  historical 
and  individual  inhibition,  to  favour  conception  by  restricting 
mental  seeing,  appears  clearly  as  an  important  factor  in 
mental  evolution.  Thought  requires  its  visual  images  under 
discipline — to  be  prevented  from  occupying  consciousness 
too  forcibly  or  freely  and  to  be  available  when  wanted. 
Perfect  imposition  of  perfectly  regulated  inhibition  may  be 
seldom  or  never  secured.  Any  particular  mind  may  inhibit 
too  severely  or  too  leniently.  The  varying  visualising  power, 
so  obvious  in  the  different  mental  methods  of  individuals, 
represents  different  operations  of  the  inhibitory  tendency 
which  provides  a  necessary  mental  discipline  for  images. 
These  different  operations  depend,  doubtless,  on  the  original 
mental  equipment  of  the  individual  and  also  on  his  surround- 
ings and  life.  They  are  usually  spontaneous  and  unwitting, 
though  educationalists  contemplate  the  rational  superintend- 

1  Instinct  and  the  Unconscious,  pp.  10  ff. 

2Bergson,  Mind-Energy  (Carr  s  Trans.),  pp.  161-162. 


VISUAL   IMAGES,   WOBDS  AND   DREAMS.  331 

ence  of  the  visualising  faculty.  There  are,  doubtless,  all 
degrees  of  visualistic  inhibition — it  is  almost  absent  in  a. 
mind  like  Blake's  and  almost  complete  in  a  mind  like 
Watson's.  It  passes  also,  doubtless,  in  different  degrees  in 
different  minds,  into  what  Eivers  calls  "  fusion  ".l  The 
significance  of  any  idea,  such  as  the  idea  of  a  horse,  may 
centre  on  the  word  "  horse "  and  be  supported  by  visual 
images  which  lurk  underneath  it  without  entering  conscious- 
ness. These  lurking  images  may,  escaping  inhibition  or 
relieved  from  it,  become  conscious  and  visualistically  enforce 
the  meaning  or  significance  of  the  idea  which  centred  on  the 
word.  These  entrant  images,  or  any  one  of  them,  may  substi- 
tute an  imaged  focus  for  the  original  verbal  focus.  This  is 
inhibition  in  its  suppressive  and  releasing  aspects.  Visual 
experiences  of  matters  connected  with  horses  may  cease  to 
be  recoverable  as  images  and  still  contribute  to  significance 
by  incorporation  in  the  mental  process  stirred  by  the  word. 
This  is  Rivers'  "fusion".  There  may  be,  also,  a  complete 
deletion  of  the  effects  of  some  experiences  upon  the  mind, 
corresponding  to  the  complete  obliviscence  suffered  by  memory. 
The  mind  may  retain  no  traces  of  some  experiences,  though  it 
may  be  that  no  experience  does  not  leave  some  permanent 
result.  There  may  be  a  slight  deflexion,  though  it  may  be 
virtually  irrelevant,  to  mark  the  former  touch  of  any  experi- 
ence, however  fleeting  and  imperceptible  it  may  appear  to* 
be. 

It  has  been  implied  that  words  are  the  inhibiting  agents  in 
devisualisation  and  they  seem  to  have  this  role.  Since  they 
are  themselves  visual  images  which  appear  in  thinking  (only 
the  visual  aspect  of  imaging  is  under  discussion  here)  they 
intimate  a  retention  of  visualisation  which  has  dispensed 
with  visual  mimicry.  It  is  usual  to  distinguish  between 
visual  images  and  words,  even  when  the  latter  are  visualised,, 
because  words  are  visual  signs  or  hints  that  have  no  re- 
semblance to  objects  and  contain  no  element  of  imitation. 
These  visual  signs  inhibit  mimicing  visualisation  and  "  Almost 
all  highly  intellectual  activity  is  a  matter  of  words,  to  the 
nearly  total  exclusion  of  anything  else  ".  This  substitution 
of  the  word  for  the  representative  visual  image  occurs,  adds 
Bertrand  Russell,  because  words  are  more  easily  produced, 
because  images  may  contain  irrelevant  detail,  and  because 
abstract  matters  are  not  easily  rendered  by  imagery.  De- 
struction of  imagery  would  follow  these  advantages  by  throw- 
ing the  mind  entirely  on  the  resource  of  words.  It  is,  however 

1  Instinct  and  the  Unconscious,  p.  32. 


332  JOSHUA  c.  GKEGOBY: 

a  necessary  safeguard  in  thinking,  Russell  adds,  "  to  be  able, 
once  in  a  way,  to  discard  words  for  a  moment  and  contem- 
plate facts  more  directly  through  images  ".l  This  process  of 
contemplating  facts  more  directly  through  images  and,  it  may 
be  added,  of  using  them  as  vehicles  of  artistic  insight,  would, 
if  lost,  deplete  the  mind  and  might,  in  the  final  result,  even 
destroy  its  capacity  for  abstract  thought.  A  regulated  in- 
hibition of  visual  images,  which  prevents  their  intrusion  and 
allows  them  access  when  desirable,  provides  thought  with  a 
mental  method.  This  inhibition  is  normal  to  the  human 
mind,  though  the  perfection  of  its  regulation  varies  in  degree 
and  may  never  reach  the  ideal. 

Verbal  regulatory  inhibition  of  visual  imagery  is  a  com- 
promise between  thinking  in  words  and  thinking  in  pictures. 
It  is,  normally,  a  fairly  effective  co-operative  combination, 
though  either  partner,  verbalising  or  picturing,  may  secure 
mastership  in  the  co-partnery.  The  verbal  inhibition  of 
visual  imagery  is  very  discernible  in  the  literalisation  or 
stripping  of  metaphorical  words.  Words  which  begin  their 
public  career  as  metaphors  lose  their  metaphorical  signifi- 
cance and  signify  their  meaning  with  literal  directness. 
When  we  say  of  any  person  that  he  is  "in  a  hole  "  or  in 
"  a  tight  place  "  we  think  of  him  as  "  in  difficulties  "  without 
having  mental  pictures  of  the  struggles  in  an  actual  hole  or 
of  the  squeezings  between  narrow  walls  which  originally 
conferred  a  metaphorical  status  upon  the  two  phrases.  The 
metaphorical  images  are  often  there,  pinned  under  the  phrase, 
•so  to  speak,  and  ready  for  conscious  adoption.  Now  the 
dream  discards  the  inhibiting  words  and  summons  the 
images.  Dreams  are  eminently  visualising  achievements  and 
Freud  notes  that  they  transform  verbal  connexions  into  con- 
nexions between  images.  Picture  writing  has  serious  diffi- 
culties with  the  logical  relations  expressed  by  "if"  or  other 
similar  words  and  the  picture  writing  of  the  dream  appears 
more  chaotic  than  waking  thought  because  it  is  deprived  of 
verbal  aids  to  conceiving  these  connexions.  Causation  may 
occur  in  the  dream  as  SUCCESSION  :  this,  it  may  be  noted, 
gains  dramatically  but  loses  conceptually — the  word  "  cause  " 
MEANS  more  than  a  mere  succession,  however  graphic  it  may 
be.  Freud  adds  that  words  play  a  part  in  the  formation  of 
dreams  and  he  speaks  of  them  as  junction  points  for  many 
conceptions  and  as  having  a  predestined  ambiguity.2  The 
restoration  of  their  original  picturesque  meaning  to  words 

1  The  Analysis  of  Mind,  p.  212. 

2  The  Interpretation  of  Dreams  (Brill's  Trans.),  ch.  vi. 


VISUAL   IMAGES,  WOEDS  AND   DREAMS.  333 

which  are  now  abstract  is  specially  significant  in  relation  to- 
verbal  inhibition  of  images.  Freud  chooses  as  instances  of 
demetaphorised  phrases  "  in  a  hole"  and  "in  a  tight  place," 
and  Nicoll l  records  a  dream  that  releases  the  images  from 
their  inhibitory  under- pinning  by  them.  A  young  man  was 
unwilling  to  accept  an  offered  post  and  faced  with  the  al- 
ternatives of  unacceptable  work  or  unemployment.  In  his 
waking  thought  he  was  in  "  a  tight  place  ".  He  dreamed  he 
was  in  a  cave  which  connected  with  the  sea  by  a  long  narrow 
passage.  He  struggled  through  it  and  found  himself  battling 
in  the  surf.  The  dream  ended  on  further  incidents  but  the 
original  imprisonment  and  struggle  through  the  sea-washed 
passage  corresponds  to  the  release  from  inhibition  by  the 
verbal  phrase  of  images  which  have  an  obvious  connexion 
with  the  original  metaphor  in  the  words  "in  a  tight  place  ". 
Nicoll,  in  his  interpretation  of  the  dream,  hankers  after  birth 
symbolism  and  compares  the  cave,  with  its  passage,  to  the 
womb.  Imagery  released  from  verbal  inhibition  and  drawn 
directly  from  familiar  experience  is  a  simpler  and  more 
natural  explanation. 

The  dream  appears  to  reveal  the  inhibitory  sojourn  of 
visual  images  beneath  the  inhibiting  verbal  images.  Ex- 
pressed in  terms  of  mental  process  or  reaction,  the  tendency 
to  visualise  words  during  thinking  shuts  down  the  tendency 
to  visualise  images.  When  thinking  proceeds  without  words 
the  shut-down  tendency  becomes,  assertive.  This  assertive- 
ness  runs  riot  in  the  dream  because  verbal  thought  has 
almost  disappeared.  The  disappearance  of  visual  word- 
images  is  a  striking  feature  of  the  world  of  dreams.  Intense 
visualisation  sometimes  contains  visualised  words :  "  I  write 
when  commanded  by  the  spirits,"  wrote  Blake,  "and  the 
moment  I  have  written,  I  see  the  words  fly  about  in  all 
directions".2  Seers,  however,  more  often  hear  words  than 
see  them  and  dreamers,  who  are  embryo  Blakes,  seldom  see 
words  in  their  dreams.  Dreamers  have  seen  some  casual 
and  curious  combinations  of  letters  but,  though  printed  or 
written  words  pervade  modern  civilisation  and  are  constantly 
before  men's  eyes,  the  dream-world  is  largely  a  wordless 
world  and  visual  images  are  there  supreme. 

Many  dreams  appear  to  transcribe  thoughts  directly  into 
pictures  by  discarding  the  verbal  expression  and  releasing  the 
inhibited  images.  A  gentleman  arranged  a  hen-run,  during 
the  tight  time  of  the  war,  by  surrounding  his  garden  with 

1  Dream  Psychology,  ch.  v. 

2  Poems  of  William  Blake,  Edit.  Yeats  :  Introd. 


334    j.  c.  GREGORY:  VISUAL  IMAGES,  WORDS  AND  DREAMS. 

fish-netting.  He  remarked  to  his  mother:  "I  hope  no  cat 
will  break  through  the  nets  ".  He  happened  to  read,  during 
^the  next  afternoon,  of  the  were-wolf  legend  and  was  reminded, 
by  a  natural  association,  of  the  cognate  superstition  that 
witches  can  transform  themselves  into  cats.  That  night  he 
dreamed  of  his  garden  :  he  stood  where  a  torn  piece  of  netting 
waved  in  the  wind.  Then  he  was  conscious  of  commotion, 
of  a  creature  passing  behind  him,  of  a  chase,  of  a  capture  and 
of  holding  a  woman  in  his  arms.  On  looking  into  her  face 
he  saw  it  wrinkled,  withered  and  lined,  as  though  she  had 
lived  for  aeons.  He  had  thought  with  the  images  released 
from  under  his  former  words.  The  witch  of  his  dream, 
emphatically  imaged  by  her  wrinkled  face,  was  the  "cat" 
of  his  thought — an  obvious  metamorphosis  through  associa- 
tion. 

If  these  images  had  entered  his  mind  as  he  spoke  to  his 
mother,  they  would  have  been  under  some  measure  of 
inhibitory  restraint  and  he  would  not  have  visualised  a  fear 
into  an  actual  occurrence.  This  displacement  of  meaning 
occurred  in  the  dream,  after  the  usual  manner  of  dreaming. 
Images  under  the  inhibitory  discipline  of  words  signified  a 
fear,  the  same  images  freed  from  restraint  signified  an  actual, 
and  illusory,  event.  Dream-metamorphoses  of  thoughts  into 
illusory  events  intimate  both  the  verbal  inhibition  of  images 
and  some  advantages  of  such  inhibiting.  Thought  tends  to 
resolve  into  a  survey  of  images  if  visualisation  is  unrestrained. 
This  survey  runs  in  the  dream  to  its  completion  in  hallucina- 
tion. Schleiermacher  regarded  dreaming  as  a  replacement 
of  thoughts  by  hallucinations  : l  this  seems  to  be  true  and  to 
be  true  because  the  mind  turns  from  words  to  images. 
Thinking  is  achieved  through  the  subjection  of  images, 
through  words  which  inhibit  them  and  control  their  appear- 
ances in  consciousness.  This  disciplined  visualisation  is 
appreciated  through  its  reversions  to  indiscipline.  When 
minds  are  assaulted  by  their  images  they  reel,  as  Blake's 
mind  often  reeled.  When  they  are  periodically  assaulted  in 
dreams  they  plunge  into  illusion.  These  are  "  flagrant  in- 
stances "  of  the  intractableness  of  the  visual  image.  Words 
subdue  this  intractableness  and  conform  it  to  the  logic  of 
thought.  Extreme  devisualisation  may  err  by  excess  of 
discipline  as  extreme  visualisation  may  err  by  deficit.  Those 
little  dramas  that  we  call  dreams  are  periodical  reminders  of 
the  regulatory  inhibition  exercised  over  visual  images  by 
words  and  of  its  necessity  for  thought. 

1  Freud,  The  Interpretation  of  Dreams  (Brill's  Trans. ),  ch.  i. 


V.— DISCUSSIONS. 
A  WORD  ABOUT  "COHERENCE". 

VERY  probably  students  of  philosophy  are  tired  of  discussions  about 
4t  Coherence  ".  The  vitality  of  the  opposition  to  it  certainly  makes 
one  think.  It  seems  as  if  the  simple  doctrine  "  Truth  is  when  the 
fact  exists  as  the  proposition  says  "  was  so  overwhelmingly  plain  and 
convincing  that  very  great  authorities  have  finally  settled  down  to 
acquiescence  in  it.  It  is,  of  course,  plausible ;  especially  if  you 
take  the  distinction  that  the  above  is  the  description  of  truth, 
though  the  test,  or  criterion,  or  procedure  towards  the  attainment, 
of  truth  may  be  something  further. 

An  elementary  mode  of  statement — nothing  profound  or  ambitious 
— has  occurred  to  me,  which  I  should  like  to  be  allowed  to  suggest. 
It  is  merely  this  ;  that  the  advocates  of  "  correspondence  "  are 
speaking  of  truth  in  the  everyday  sense,  while  we  who  demand 
"  coherence  "  do  not  think  you  ought  to  speak  seriously  or  theoretic- 
ally of  truth  unless  you  have  proof. 

"  I  have  truth  when  I  make  a  proposition  to  which  the  facts 
correspond  "  or  "  which  corresponds  to  the  facts  ".  Of  course,  this 
is  universally  accepted  in  daily  intercourse.  If  I  am  told  there  is 
a  train  at  nine  A.M.,  and  there  really  is  one,  then  I  am  told  the 
truth.  The  truth  is  the  meaning  of  certain  words.  The  fact  is  a 
touchstone,  a  test,  outside  and  of  a  different  kind. 

So  far  so  good.  But  we  should  say,  I  suppose,  that  "  the  fact  " 
here  is  much  too  simply  taken  for  anything  serious  to  hang  on  it. 
It  is  all  right  as  long  as  there  is  no  reason  for  doubt ;  but  the 
moment  there  is  room  for  doubt,  and  you  ask  how  you  are  to  know 
whether  the  proposition  is  true  or  not,  you  must  take  the  step  of 
asking  for  proof. 

Now  here  you  meet  with  something  remarkable.  Of  what  is  the 
proof  to  l>e  ?  Prima  facie,  of  the  proposition ;  you  allege  the  existing 
fact,  and  then,  on  the  everyday  assumption,  the  truth  of  the  pro- 
position is  proved. 

But  this  omits  a  very  familiar  procedure.  It  is  surely  natural 
and  not  uncommon  to  ask  for  proof  of  the  fact.  If  the  fact,  which 
we  used  as  a  test,  is  not  proved,  then  the  test  fails  and  the  truth  of 
the  proposition  is  not  established.  Now  what  sort  of  thing  is  the 
proof  of  a  fact  ?  Two  points  are  clear,  surely  ;  it  is  a  procedure  by 
coherence  ;  and  it  is  the  same  procedure  as  the  proof  of  the  truth  of 
the  proposition  which  affirms  it. 


336      BEBNAED  BOSANQUET  :   A  WORD  ABOUT   "  COHEKENCE  ". 

The  first  point  needs  no  argument.  The  procedure  of  science  or 
of  a  law  court  settles  the  question  at  once.  The  test  is,  "  to  save 
the  appearances  " — to  get  the  result  which  gives  the  highest  degree 
of  agreement  in  all  the  relevant  experiences. 

And  the  second  point  shows  that  the  establishment  of  the  fact 
and  the  establishment  of  the  truth  which  it  is  supposed  to  test  are 
one  and  the  same  thing.  "  Caesar  was  murdered."  This  is  true, 
if  his  murder  really  took  place.  Yes,  but  did  his  murder  really  take 
place  ?  The  answer  to  this  question  rests  of  course  on  an  enormous 
construction  of  critical  theory  and  harmonised  facts — the  proof. 
If  the  fact  is  not  proved,  the  truth  of  the  proposition  tested  by  it  is 
not  established,  and  you  cannot  say  the  proposition  is  true. 

You  may  take  it  ideally — hypothetically ;  and  I  think  this  is 
sometimes  done.  You  may  say  "  If  the  fact  is  real,  the  proposition 
is  true  "  ;  or  "  that  is  what  I  mean  by  the  proposition  being  true, 
viz.,  that  the  fact  is  real ".  Speaking  from  memory,  I  think  this  is 
Dr.  McTaggart's  line. 

The  only  objection  that  I  see  to  this,  is  that  it  puts  you  in  the 
position  of  habitually  speaking  about  propositions  as  true  when  you 
do  not  in  the  least  know  whether  they  are  true  or  not.  And  this 
seems  to  me  a  very  dangerous  habit,  though  necessary  up  to  a 
certain  point. 

I  suppose  it  is  the  legitimacy  of  this  mode  of  speech  that  Croce 
defends  when  he  says  that  we  are  entitled  to  affirm  about  great 
historical  events  that  "  humanity  remembers  them,"  apart,  as  I 
understand  him,  from  any  critical  proof.  (Suppose  you  say  that 
"  Humanity  remembers  "  the  Eesurrection.  I  should  admit  there 
is  a  sense  in  which  you  may  say  this  ;  but  not  a  strict  sense.)  All 
I  assert  is,  that  we  are  in  the  wrong,  if  in  saying  that  truth  depends 
on  fact,  we  forget  that  fact  depends  on  proof,  and  proof,  we  may 
add,  constantly  and  in  a  large  measure  depends  on  truth.  The 
apparent  difference  of  kind  disappears  on  analysis.  I  do  not  want 
to  disregard  the  convenience  of  the  innumerable  degrees  of  certainty 
which  we  practically  accept  in  daily  life.  Only  a  philosopher  of 
Laputa  would  do  so.  But  I  do  say  that  for  logical  theory  and  in 
principle  you  only  have  truth  where  your  fact  is  proved  ;  that  is, 
where  your  proposition  is  exhibited  as  immanent  in  a  system  where 
all  relevant  experience  is  included. 

This  is  as  far,  I  think,  as  the  current  "  correspondence  "  theory 
takes  you.  A  further  point  is  raised  if  you  ask  whether  logical 
laws  have  to  be  assumed  apart  from  coherence  ;  but  that  I  spoke 
of  in  the  April  MIND,  and  I  do  not  think  the  current  defence  of 
"  correspondence  "  raises  it. 

BEBNAED  BOSANQUET. 


RELATIVITY,  SCIENTIFIC  AND  PHILOSOPHICAL. 

I  SHOULD  like  to  disclaim  altogether  the  "  Gallio  attitude"  which 
Dr.  Carr  imputes  to  critics  of  his  philosophical  interpretation  of 
the  Theory  of  Kelativity.1  Far  from  expressing  "indifference  to 
the  new  discovery"  I  fully  admitted  both  its  outstanding  scientific 
value  and  its  philosophic  importance.2  But  I  still  think  Dr. 
Carr  misreads  its  significance  as  regards  the  philosophical  prin- 
ciple of  relativity. 

His  argument  falls  into  two  distinct  stages.  The  first  is  based 
on  admitted  results  of  the  Theory ;  but  the  second  interprets  these 
results  in  a  manner  which  the  Theory  itself  in  no  degree  justifies, 
although  his  conclusions  may,  of  course,  on  other  grounds,  be 
true ;  but  with  any  other  grounds  than  the  Theory  itself  we  are 
not  at  present  concerned.  I  believe  I  anticipated  this  second 
stage  in  saying  that  philosophic  relativity  is  concerned  "  with 
the  relation  between  mind  and  its  content,  or  between  mind 
and  reality,  and  applies  universally " ; 3  and  I  shall  try  to 
show  very  briefly  the  untenability  of  his  position  in  more 
detail.  We  begin  then  with  the  truth  that  "  there  is  no  absolute 
event  in  an  independent  system"4  (p.  176).  This  is  the  essence 
of  the  Theory,  and  the  first  stage  of  Dr.  Carr's  argument.  The 
next  question  is  as  to  the  nature  of  this  independence  and  system  ; 
and  it  is  here  that  we  find  what  I  take  to  be  an  altogether  illegiti- 
mate expansion  of  the  Theory's  implications.  With  the  character 
of  the  independence  which  the  Theory  repudiates  I  have  already 
dealt.  "  The  independence  that  is  denied  subsists  not  between  the 
mind  and  observations,  but  between  our  scales  and  units  and  the 
observed  phenomena  "  (p.  46).  Thus  the  independent  system  for 
Einstein  is  physical ;  or  if  we  employ  a  category  purely  philo- 
sophic, it  is  ontological.  But  at  this  point  Dr.  Carr  crosses  the 
Eubicon,  and  the  second  part  of  his  argument  begins.  For  he 
straightway  transforms  this  ontological  into  an  epistemological 
category  : — "  the  absolute  is  not  in  the  object  of  knowledge  taken  in 
abstraction,  not  in  the  external  world,  it  is  in  the  observer  or  subject 
of  knowledge  and  a  function  of  his  activity."  5  When  we  take  the 

1  MIND,  April,  1922,  p.  169.    For  "Theory"  c/.,  ante,  p.  42,  note  3. 

2  Ante,  p.  52  ;   "epoch-making,"  p.  47.  3P.  44. 

4  "  .  .  .  and  no  sameness  of  events  occurring  to  different  observers." 
This  seems  to  ignore  the  identity  of  observations  within  any  one  reference 
system.     Cf.t  ante,  p.  42. 
'  5  P.  174.     Italics  mine. 


338  J.  E.  TUENEE: 

two  statements  literally,  the  fallacy  of  this  transition  becomes 
obvious.  The  relativist's  system  of  reference  (which  is  undoubtedly 
part  of  the  external  world)  is  transformed  into  the  "  object  of 
knowledge"  and  transferred  from  the  external  world  to  the  ob- 
server. Or  take  an  alternative  statement.  "  The  phenomena  of 
nature  must  be  relative  to  a  standard" — this  standard  being  for 
Einstein  once  more  the  observer's  system  of  reference.  But  again 
the  same  transformation  occurs,  and  Dr.  Carr  converts  this  into 
"a  standard  ftirnished  by  the  observer".1  The  two  positions  are, 
obviously,  far  from  being  identical.  We  may  hold  the  first  without 
accepting  the  second ;  and  if  we  do  advance  to  the  second  it  must 
be  on  grounds  altogether  independent  of  the  Theory.  The  question 
becomes — Is  the  relativist's  reference  system  a  standard  furnished 
by  the  observer  ?  I  venture  to  think  that  this  epistemological  pro- 
blem is  as  foreign  to  many  physicists  as  relativity  mathematics  is 
to  the  majority  of  philosophers.  It  is  indeed  a  problem  which  can 
never  be  solved  on  any  purely  scientific  basis  such  as  underlies  the 
Theory.  The  only  science  which  can  be  appealed  to  is  the  science 
of  knowledge.  The  issue,  that  is,  is  epistemological ;  it  cannot 
therefore  be  affected  by  the  scientific  Theory  in  any  way.2  It  is 
well  known  again  that  Dr.  Whitehead  emphasises  the  total  ex- 
clusion of  mind  from  the  realm  of  Nature  for  all  purposes  of 
science.  Thus  his  position  is  diametrically  opposed  to  Dr.  Carr's  ; 
but  he,  at  least,  cannot  be  charged  with  "  caring  for  none  of  these 
things  ". 

Dr.  Carr,  in  short,  has  unwarrantably  altered  the  venue  of  the 
whole  enquiry.  The  introduction  of  the  category  of  knowledge  is 
justified  by  no  earlier  consideration  whatever ;  it  is  gratuitous  and 
irrelevant  to  the  Theory  as  such.  We  must  not  be  misled  by  the 
fact  that  the  objects — the  reference  system — with  which  the  Theory 
is  concerned  are  "  objects  of  knowledge  ".  That  is  a  truism  ;  for  if 
they  were  not  there  could  be  no  Theory.  But  this  is  far  from 
proving  the  truth  of  philosophical  relativity:  Of  course  if  Dr. 
Carr's  philosophic  position  had  already  been  indubitably  established 
then  the  Theory  would  have  provided  for  it  invaluable  confirmation. 
But  to  confirm  an  established  principle  is  one  thing  ;  indirectly  to 
prove  by  implication  a  principle  which  itself  is  in  question  is 
quite  another ;  and  it  is  precisely  this  conversion  of  the  ontological 
system  into  an  epistemological  basis  which  is  disputed.  The 
absolute,  we  have  seen,  is  "  in  the  observer  ".  But  further,  it  is 
"  the  '  I  think '  which  in  affirming  its  activity  posits  existence. 
The  '  I  think  '  does  not  presuppose  existence  ;  it  is  not  generated 
but  generator  "  (p.  174).  This  standpoint  is  analogous  to,  if  not 

1  P.  175.     My  italics.     C/.,  "The  ground  of  measure-relations  must  be 
physical  in  nature  ".      Schlick,  Space  and  Time,  p.  59. 

2  There  is  t  a  minor  but  still  important  point.     Dr.  Carr  argues  that 
"Our   'I  think'  is  attached  to  a  system  of  reference  from  (which)  we 
derive  our  axes  "  (p.  175).     In  the  Theory,  however,  the  axes  themselves 
constitute  part  of  the  system — they  are  not  derived  from  it. 


EELATIVITY,   SCIENTIFIC  AND   PHILOSOPHICAL.  339 

identical  with,  that  of  Italian  neo-idealism,  where  we  have  "  mind 
as  the  transcendental  activity  productive  of  the  objective  world  of 
experience  "-1  I  have  already  accepted  "  mind  as  one,  if  not  the 
sole,  clue  to  the  nature  of  Eeality  ".2  But  I  take  this  to  mean  no 
more  than  that  finite  mind  is  (a}  directly  revelatory  of  reality,  and 
therefore  (b)  shares  a  common  nature  with  reality  ;  there  is  between 
them  no  absolute  difference  nor  fundamental  opposition.  Their 
common  nature  constitutes,  of  course,  a  problem.  I  take  it  to  be 
wholeness — totality — the  Hegelian  self-transcending  ideality  of  the 
finite.  If  this  is  what  Dr.  Carr  means  by  philosophic  relativity, 
then  our  only  difference  is  that  he  regards  it  as  finally  proved  by 
the  Theory,  whereas  I  fail  to  see  any  direct  connexion  between 
them.  Subject  to  later  qualification  I  will  admit,  with  Lord 
Haldane,  that  knowledge  is  "  foundational  of  reality  ".  But  this 
does  not  mean  that  "  the  '  I  think  '  is  not  generated  but  generator". 
What  are  the  implications  of  Dr.  Carr's  contention  ?  Sense- 
experience  alone  becomes  "  the  immediate  object  of  consciousness, 
and  from  it  therefore  the  physical  reality  of  science  is  constituted  ". 
Now  what  exactly  is  covered  and  implied  by  "  sense-experience  " 
is  still  matter  of  dispute  ;  here  it  is  sufficient  to  point  out  that  Dr. 
Carr  equates  all  "  sense-experience  " — in  principle — to  pain — that 
is  to  what  all  schools  alike  accept  as  a  permanently  localised  and 
subjective  affection  of  the  individual  percipient.  In  this  equivalence 
there  is  of  course  an  element  of  truth ;  but  it  is  not  yet  finally  estab- 
lished as  an  ultimate  principle,  and  it  is  certainly  not  directly  implied 
by  Einstein's  Theory.3  Still  further,  "  the  principle  yields  in  the 
first  place  a  mathematics  (which)  can  offer  material  to  physics. 
Physics  depends  on  mathematics,  not  vice  versa,  and  mathematics 
becomes  an  empirical  instead  of  a  transcendental  science."  4  Much 
depends  here  on  the  precise  meaning  of  "  transcendental "  and 
"  empirical  "  ;  but  in  any  case  the  statement  is  correct  only  within 
limitations.  Relativity  mathematics  certainly  applies  to  some 
important  branches  of  physics,  but  it  only  expands  and  corrects 
earlier  mathematics  ;  the  general  relation  between  the  two  sciences 
still  remains  unaltered,  and  the  pathway  from  "  sense-experience  " 
to  mathematics  still  traverses  physics  in  the  first  place  ;  although 
at  later — but  more  abstract — stages  it  is  almost  impossible  to  dis- 
tinguish between  them.  To  maintain  the  contrary  is  to  adopt 
Prof.  Eddington's  fallacious  argument  based  on  the  "  embryo 
mind  "  ; 5  nor  can  we  disregard  Dr.  Campbell's  contention  that 
"  integration  leads  to  physically  significant  results  only  because  it 

1  Gentile,  Theory  of  Mind  as  Pure  Act,  p.  43.  2MiND,  ante,  p.  46. 

3  If  the  Theory  is  accepted  in  the  light  of  the  unconscious  subjectivism 
which  has  so  long  dominated  science  then  such  a  position  is  presupposed  ; 
but  this  again  is  not  proof.     Against   this  subjectivism   there  has  for- 
tunately set  in  a  strong  reaction,  of  which  Dr.  Whitehead's  Concept  of 
Nature  is  perhaps  the  best  known — but  not  the  only — expression. 

4  P.  173.     My  italics.     Cf.,  Appendix  (2). 

5  MIND,  April,  1921),  p.  154.      The  Journal  of  Philosophy,  vol.  xvii., 
p.  610. 


340  J.  E.  TUBNEE: 

corresponds  step  by  step  to  some  physical  process  "  ;  and  Lord 
Haldane's  opinion  that  "  Einstein  seems  to  think  that  we  perceive 
objects,  not  events.  The  continuum  is  got  at  indirectly  by  in- 
ference, and  is  not  the  actual  basis  of  nature  as  directly  known."  l 
Physics,  that  is,  is  still  prior  to  mathematics. 

But  the  truth  that  knowledge  is  foundational  of  reality  itself 
demands  substantial  qualification.  For  finite  knowledge  declares 
that  to  itself  reality  is  foundational.  Whether  we  can  say — No 
finite  knowledge,  no  reality — seems  to  me  questionable ;  but 
certainly  we  must  say — No  reality,  no  finite  knowledge.  For  it 
is  with  finite  knowledge  that  we  are  here  concerned,  and  to  such 
knowledge  reality  is  foundational ;  it  is  "  generator,"  and  knowledge 
"generated".  Hence  their  common  nature ;  hence  it  is  too  that 
infinite  knowledge  is  one  with  reality.  But  throughout  Dr.  Carr's 
discussion  there  runs  that  unjustifiable  identification  of  physical 
phenomena  with  experience,  which  begs  the  whole  question  at 
issue.  We  find  e.g.  (p.  171)  that  "the  principle  interprets  the 
behavioiir  "  of  the  filings ;  it  deals  i.e.,  with  "  interpretation  of  the 
phenomena  " ;  but  on  page  177  the  position  is  that "  the  principle 
asks  us  ...  to  interpret"  experience;  again  the  initial  ontological 
issues  become  illogically  presented  as  epistemological ;  "  sense- 
experience  presents  itself  in  the  form  of  event"  (p.  174). 2 

One  minor  point  seems  to  be  important.  "  The  principle 
interprets  the  behaviour  of  .  .  .  phenomena."  But  it  seems  to  me 
that  the  Theory  offers  itself  primarily  as  a  description,  and  not  as 
an  interpretation  in  any  philosophic  sense  of  explanation.3  The 
ideal  of  many  relativists  appears  to  be  to  dispense  with  explanation 
altogether  and  to  content  themselves  with  descriptions — needless 
to  say  of  the  greatest  value.  They  regard  it  as  their  province  to 
describe  phenomena  in  exact  geometrical  or  mathematical  terms, 
but  not  to  explain  them ;  just  as  a  bank  passbook  describes  transac- 
tions which  it  does  not  explain ; 4  and  both  the  clerk  and  the 
relativist  lighten  their  tasks  appreciably  by  this  procedure.  But 

1  Physics,  The  Elements,  p.  523.     The  Reign  of  Relativity,  p.  110  (con- 
densed).    Also  Einstein  and  the  Universe,  p.  5  ;  "  mathematical  symbolism 
always  embodies  an  abstraction ".     "Starting  from  familiar  conceptions 
...  we  are  finally  left  with  Space  and  Time  in  the  simple  form  (of) 
Einstein's  physics.  .  .  .  Reflections  in  the  realm  of   metrical  geometry 
acquire  a  meaning  only  when  its  relationship  to  physics  is  borne  in  mind." 
Schlick,  op.  cit.,  pp.  5,  59. 

2  Cf.,  Dr.  Bosanquet.     "  The  moral  of  relativity  is  not  the  permeation 
of  the  universe  by  mind  or  minds  "  ;  (Meeting  of  Extremes,  p.  16) ;  and 
Dr.  Whitehead's  realistic  theory  of  events  in  his  Concept  of  Nature. 

3  Cf.,    p.    171.     "According    to    the    theory,   this    is    the    scientific 
expl*  nation." 

4  Cf.,  MIND,  ante,  p.  47,  note  1 ;  also  pp.  200,  204  (Dr.  Dorothy  Wrinch)  : 
"all  use  Space  as  a  description.     It  is  the  properties  and  not  the  intrinsic 
nature  of  space  which  is  the  subject  of  investigation."     My  statement  is 
intended  as  one  of  general  principle,  subject  to  exceptions  on  minor 
aspects  of  detail ;  just  as  mere  dates  in  the  passbook  may  explain  a  great 
deal.     Cj.j  further  Appendix  (1). 


EELATIVITY,   SCIENTIFIC  AND  PHILOSOPHICAL.          341 

philosophy  must  seek  explanations ;  further,  description,  as  such, 
can  never  take  the  place  of  explanation,  though  it  may  provide 
material  for  its  correction.  The  Principle  of  Equivalence  e.g., 
merely  states  that  gravitational  phenomena  may  be  equally  well 
described  or  expressed  in  terms  of  acceleration.1  But  to  remain 
satisfied  with  the  suggestion  that  accelerated  motion  is  a  neces-ary 
consequence  of  the  space-time  continuum  surely  betrays  a  degenera- 
tion of  philosophic  fibre. 

There  is  another  possible  source  of  confusion.  Dr.  Carr  refers 
to  "scientific"  and  "physical  reality"  (pp.  173,  174,  176).  I  pre- 
sume no  ultimate  distinction  is  implied  between  these  and  some 
other  mode  of  reality — though  there  is  of  course  a  subordinate 
distinction  of  aspect  or  standpoint.  If  on  the  other  hand  these 
terms  refer  to  scientific  concepts,  then  these  of  course — like  all 
concepts — arise  from  a  basis  of  sense-experience ;  the  "  I  think  " 
is  their  generator.  But  while  we  all  employ  the  statements  that 
"  time — matter — space — are  concepts  "  these  are,  taken  literally, 
false.  Space,  etc.,  are  for  philosophy  reals,  not  concepts  ;  although 
they  are  reals  of  which  we  form  concepts ;  and  concepts  themselves 
are  also  real. 

Finally  as  to  a  few  obscurities  of  expression.  "Simultaneity 
and  direction  have  been  falsified  by  experiment "  (p.  176).  The 
Theory,  however,  so  far  as  experiment  is  involved,  depends  on 
coincidence,  and  therefore  on  simultaneity.  "  The  absolute  observa- 
tion is,  whether  or  not  the  coincidence  exists,  not  when  or  where 
or  under  what  circumstances  it  exists."2  Again,  is  the  reality  of 
the  universe  finite — "  finite  yet  unbounded  "  (p.  177) — or  its  extent  ?  3 
and  in  what  sense  can  the  universe  be  finite  because  "  every  straight 
line  is  a  geodesic  which  at  infinity  must  return  on  itself  "  ? 

I  conclude  then  that  if  any  form  of  subjective  idealism  has  been 
already  established,  or  is  presupposed,  then  the  Theory  amply  con- 
firms that  philosophy.  On  the  other  hand,  the  Theory  itself 
cannot  substantiate  it ;  it  is  indeed  equally  consonant  with  either 
objective  idealism,  realism,  or  even  materialism ;  it  is,  for  philo- 
sophy, a  benevolent  neutral. 

APPENDIX. 

Since  the  above  was  written,  two  lectures  by  Einstein  have  been 
published.4  Although  these  deal  with  ether  and  geometry,  and  so 
might  easily  lend  themselves  to  a  subjectivist  interpretation,  they 
seem  to  me  strongly  to  confirm  the  "  neutrality  "  of  the  Theory 

144 It  is  impossible  to  distinguish  between  a  universal  force  and  a 
curvature  of  the  manifold."  Prof.  Lmdemann  in  Schlick,  op.  cit.,  p.  iv. 

2 Prof.  Eddington,  Space  Time  and  Gravitation,  p.  87  ;  c/.,  ibid.— "So 
far  as  knowledge  is  knowledge  of  intersections  of  world  lines,  it  is 
absolute  knowledge  independent  of  the  observer".  (My  italics.)  Cf., 
Schlick,  op.  cit.,  pp.  50-53. 

3  Cf.,  MIND,  ante,  p.  45,  note  3.     Schlick,  ibid.,  p.  73. 

4  Sidelights  on  Relativity. 


342  J.   E.   TUKNEE  :   EELATIVITY. 

if  there  is  any  definite  tendency  at  all,  it  is  realistic.     Here  I  can 
only,  however,  append  a  few  relevant  quotations. 

(1)  It  is  extremely  interesting   to  notice   that   as  the   Theory 
develops  it  turns  more  and  more  from  description  to  explanation — 
even  to  causal  explanation.     As  regards  matter  and  the  continuum, 
e.g.,  the  latter  now  ceases  to  be  in  itself  ultimate.     Its  "  metrical 
qualities  .  .  .  are  partly  conditioned  by  the  matter  outside  of  the 
territory  under  consideration  .  .  .  ether  determines  the  metrical 
relations,  the  configurative  possibilities  of  solid  bodies  as  well  as 
the  gravitational  fields  ". 1     Except  that  ether  and  matter  have  new 
attributes,  this  is  little  removed  from  the  older  physics. 

(2)  As  to  the  nature  of  mathematics,  Einstein's  position  is  quite 
definite ;  for  him  mathematics  is  "  transcendental ".     "As  far  as 
the  laws  of  mathematics  refer  to  reality,  they  are  not  certain ;  and 
as  far  as  they  are  certain,  they  do  not  refer  to  reality.     The  logical- 
formal  alone  forms  the  subject-matter  of  mathematics,  which  is  not 
concerned  with  the  intuitive  or  other  content.     This  view  purges 
mathematics  of  all  extraneous  elements.    That  which  gives  "  point," 
etc.,  substance  is  not  relevant  to  mathematics.     We  distinguish 
"  practical  geometry  "  from  "  purely  axiomatic  geometry  ".     All 
linear  measurement  in  physics  is  "  practical  geometry  "  ".2     We 
have  here  obviously  an  almost  absolute  dualism  which  underlies 
Einstein's  entire  treatment  of  this  point.      Scientifically  it  is  of 
course  quite   justifiable.     But  it  is  philosophically  unsound,  and 
could  be  removed,  I  think,  by  a  stricter  logical  analysis ;  but  with 
this  the  scientist,  as  such,  is  not  concerned. 

(3)  This  is  also  true,  it  seems  to  me,  of  a  still  more  important 
consequence  of  the  Theory — the  finitude  of  the  universe.     This 
finitude  is  spatial — "  spatially  unbounded  and  of  finite  magnitude  ".3 
But  this  "  spatial "  finitude  is  to  some  degree  at  least  fallacious ; 
it  is  spatial  only  within  limitations  and  under  definite  conditions ; 
it  is  perhaps  best  described  as  quasi-spatial.     For  the  term  "  space  " 
has  changed  fundamentally  in  meaning — a  change  perfectly  legiti- 
mate once  it  is  recognised  and  adhered  to.     "  Space  is  endowed 
with  physical  qualities ;  in  this  sense  there  exists  an  ether.     Space 
without  ether  is  unthinkable"  (p.  23).     All  this  restricts  the  pro- 
blem to  the  ontological  and  physical  realm.     The  physical  universe 
of  matter — ether — energy — is  finite.    Hence  the  fallacy  of  expressing 
this  in  spatial  terms.     For  it  is  obvious  from  Einstein's  treatment 
that  the  finitude  is,  strictly,  a  numerical  finitude,  not  necessarily  a 
purely  spatial  finitude  in  the  older  sense  of  extensional.     The  pro- 
blem of  extensional  infinity  still  remains  to  be  faced ;  it  may  be 
academic,  but  it  is  not  illogical.     Thus  there  is  once  more  necessary 
a  precise  definition  of  all  our  terms ;  until  this  is  achieved  con- 
fusion is  inevitable.     It  is  of  course  a  logical  problem  ;  but  it  must 
be  treated  on  an  ontological  basis. 

1  Pp.  18,  20.     On  p.  20  we  have  "the  causes  which  condition  its  state  ". 
(Italics  throughout  mine.) 

2  Pp.  28-32.  3  P   21.     Cf.,  also  p.  41. 

J.    E.    TUENBB. 


VI— CEITICAL  NOTICE. 

A  Faith  that  Enquires :  The  Gilford  Lectures  delivered  in  the 
University  of  Glasgow  in  the  years  1920  and  1921.  By  Sir 
HENBY  JONES.  London  :  Macmillan  &  Co.,  1922.  Pp.  x,  361. 

THOSE  who  enjoyed  the  privilege  of  a  personal  acquaintance  with 
Sir  Henry  Jones  have  always  been  apt  to  think  that  his  published 
writings,  vigorous  and  inspiring  as  they  are,  did  not  adequately 
represent  his  power  as  a  constructive  thinker.  His  predecessor 
in  Glasgow,  who  was  also  his  master,  was  generally  regarded  as 
the  greatest  teacher  of  philosophy  in  his  time  in  Great  Britain ; 
and  he  was  also  recognised  as  being  among  the  foremost  of  philo- 
sophical writers.  Many  of  the  pupils  of  Sir  Henry  Jones  were 
inclined  to  believe  that  he  was  not  less  great  as  a  teacher  than 
Edward  Caird  himself  ;  but  as  a  writer  he  could  hardly  be  placed 
on  a  similar  level.  The  lectures  that  have  now  been  published, 
taken  in  conjunction  with  the  important  works  on  Browning  and 
on  Lotze,  may  be  held  to  place  him  as  a  philosophical  writer  on  a 
level  at  least  approximately  equal  to  that  which  belonged  to  him  as. 
a  teacher.  In  both  respects,  no  doubt,  his  dependence  upon  Caird 
is  very  obvious,  both  in  the  general  lines  of  his  thought  and  in  the 
manner  of  his  exposition.  But  there  are  characteristic  differences. 
Caird  generally  wrote  as  an  expositor  and  as  an  extremely  sym- 
pathetic critic ;  and,  though  he  led  up  with  elaborate  care  to 
definite  conclusions  which  he  emphasised  with  strong  conviction, 
yet  it  was  always  his  tendency  to  regard  the  results  as  being  of 
less  importance  than  the  process  by  which  they  were  arrived  at, 
and  as  having  hardly  any  value  apart  from  that  process.  He  used 
to  say  that  it  was  much  more  essential  that  philosophy  should  be- 
thoroughly  reasoned  than  that  it  should  lead  to  results  that  are 
either  true  or  valuable.  Jones  would  perhaps  have  agreed  with 
this  ;  but  he  had  by  nature  more  of  the  spirit  of  a  prophet,  and 
this  makes  itself  felt  in  his  writings.  He  was  always  eager  to 
reach  a  definite  conclusion  and  to  persuade  others  to  accept  it. 
The  title  of  his  Gifford  Lectures  has  been  well  chosen  to  express 
his  attitude  of  mind.  His  philosophy  was  for  him  a  faith — not  in 
the  sense  in  which  faith  is  opposed  to  knowledge  or  reason,  but  in 
the  sense  in  which  it  implies  firm  conviction  without  complete 
proof.  He  claimed  what  William  James  characterised  as  the 
'  right  to  believe,'  but  only  after  careful  enquiry.  He  describes 
his  conclusion  as  a  hypothesis  which  cannot  bo  fully  verified,  but 


344  CRITICAL  NOTICE  : 

which  can  be  seen  to  serve  as  an  interpretation  of  the  facts  so  far 
as  known.  '  It  is  not  easy,'  he  says  (p.  96),  '  to  exaggerate  the 
significance  of  hypothesis  '  ;  though  it  has  to  be  admitted  that  '  no 
hypothesis  is  completely  worked  out '  (p.  100). 

The  general  nature  of  the  hypothesis  that  he  seeks  to  put  forward 
and  defend  is  an  idealistic  theory  of  the  universe — differing,  how- 
ever, both  from  such  an  idealism  as  that  of  Mr.  Bradley  and 
Mr.  Bosanquet  and  from  that  of  Mr.  James  Ward,  and  of  course 
still  more  markedly  from  that  of  William  James  and  those  who 
are  described  as  pragmatists  or  humanists.  His  view  is  essentially 
the  Hegelian  theory  as  interpreted  by  Edward  Caird,  but  stated 
somewhat  more  positively  and  defended  more  emphatically.  The 
fundamental  assumption  may  be  briefly  stated  (p.  106)  as  '  the 
hypothesis  of  a  God  whose  wisdom  and  power  and  goodness  are 
perfect '.  Of  the  theories  that  he  rejects  he  evidently  stands 
nearest  to  the  absolutism  of  Mr.  Bradley  and  Mr.  Bosanquet,  and 
a  large  part  of  the  book  is  devoted  to  the  criticism  of  their  doctrines. 
'It  is  only/  he  says  (p.  130),  'in  such  doctrines  as  those  of 
Mr.  Bradley  and  Mr.  Bosanquet  that  a  genuine  recognition  of  the 
apparently  inconsistent  rights  of  the  finite  and  the  infinite,  and,  as 
a  consequence,  of  morality  and  religion,  makes  itself  felt.'  But  he 
proceeds  to  indicate  that  the  treatment  of  the  apparent  inconsis- 
tency by  these  two  writers  appears  to  him  to  be  in  the  end  un- 
satisfactory. The  discussion  of  this  subject  seems  to  be  the  most 
valuable  part  of  the  book ;  and,  though  it  cannot  be  adequately 
dealt  with  in  such  a  review  as  this,  an  attempt  must  be  made  to 
set  forth  the  main  line  of  argument.  The  main  points  of  difference 
are  these  :  (1)  He  conceives  the  Absolute  as  being  personal,  not 
1  super-personal,'  and  consequently  does  not  recognise  any  distinc- 
tion between  the  Absolute  and  God.  (2)  He  rejects  the  view  that 
the  human  consciousness  is  properly  to  be  characterised  as  a 
'  finite  centre  '.  (3)  As  a  consequence  of  these  differences,  he  does 
not  admit  so  sharp  an  antithesis  between  morality  and  religion  as 
is  made  by  these  writers.  (4)  Hence  also  he  is  led  to  affirm  the 
doctrine  of  human  immortality,  which  they  are  both  inclined  to 
reject.  Some  comments  on  these  four  points  of  difference  may 
be  useful. 

With  regard  to  the  first  point,  he  quotes  (p.  315)  Mr.  Bradley's 
statement  that  '  The  highest  Reality  .  .  .  must  be  super-personal,' 
and  says  that  this  is  '  a  word  to  which  I  can  attach  no  definite 
meaning  at  all '.  No  doubt  it  does  not  at  once  tell  what  it  means ; 
but  I  should  have  supposed  that  it  could  be  interpreted  as  meaning 
one  or  other  of  two  things,  either  a  Being  who  is  personal  without 
the  limitations  that  are  commonly  understood  as  being  implied  in 
the  existence  of  a  person,  or  a  unity  including  persons  together 
with  their  relations  to  one  another  (as  in  a  human  society  or  in 
the  Absolute  as  conceived  by  Mr.  McTaggart).  But  Jones's  con- 
tention, if  I  understand  him  rightly,  is  that  all  persons  transcend 
the  limitations  that  are  implied  in  their  separate  individualities, 


SIR  HENRY  JONES,  A  Faith  that  Enquires.         345 

and  that  all  persons  are  members  of  a  community  and  include 
within  themselves  certain  relations  to  others  ;  and  hence  that  all 
persons  might  be  said  to  be  super-personal.  The  distinction  be- 
tween one  person  and  another  is  thus  essentially  only  the  difference 
of  more  or  less  completeness ;  so,  instead  of  saying  that  the 
Absolute  is  super-personal,  we  should  say  rather  that  the  Absolute 
is  the  perfect  or  complete  person.  Hence  also  every  person,  so 
far  as  he  approaches  completeness,  may  be  said  to  become  identical 
with  the  Absolute.  And  thus  we  are  led  to  the  second  point. 

If  the  view  thus  taken  is  correct,  it  is  clear  that  there  is  no 
sharp  distinction  between  the  human  and  the  divine  personalities  ; 
and  that  it  is  consequently  misleading  to  lay  special  emphasis 
upon  the  finitude  of  the  human  consciousness.  Jones  expresses 
himself  with  great  boldness  and  force  about  this.  '  There  is  not 
any  limit,'  he  says  in  one  place  (p.  156),  'to  the  identification  of 
the  worshipper  and  his  God  in  a  true  religion.'  Again  (p.  77) 
'  the  infinite  perfection  of  limitless  love  actually  lives  in  man. 
Every  good  man  is  the  Child  of  God,  and  his  life  in  its  strivings 
for  goodness  is  the  divine  perfection  operating  within  him.  God 
incarnates  himself  anew  in  all  his  children.  .  .  .  Here  is  complete 
identification,  a  losing  of  one's  self  in  utter  devotion  and  dedication, 
and  at  the  same  time  that  marvellous  recovery  cf  the  self  which 
entitles  man  to  say — "  I  and  the  Father  are  one".'  Here,  as  in 
his  other  references  to  the  religious  attitude,  Jones  avails  himself 
of  Christian  expressions  ;  but  he  might  equally  well  have  quoted 
the  well-known  saying  of  the  Indian  sages — 'tat  tuam  asi '.  In 
some  respects  the  statement  '  thou  art  the  Absolute,'  addressed  to 
every  one,  is  more  impressive  and  unmistakeable  than  the  state- 
ment '  I  am  the  Absolute,'  which  might  be  taken,  and  has  been 
taken,  as  the  special  claim  of  a  single  individual.  But  I  am  in- 
clined to  think  that  both  these  modes  of  expression  should  be  used 
somewhat  sparingly.  They  seem  to  represent  only  one  aspect  of 
the  truth.  And,  of  course,  it  is  hardly  necessary  to  add  that  neither 
Jones  nor  the  Indian  sages  meant  to  deny  that  man  has  a  finite 
aspect,  as  well  as  an  infinite  one — that,  if  he  is  a  God,  he  is  still, 
as  Browning  put  it,  only  '  in  the  germ  '.  But  what  Jones  was 
protesting  against  is  the  tendency  to  speak  as  if  he  were  nothing 
more  than  a  'finite  centre'.  Not  only  may  he  transcend  his 
limitations  by  identifying  himself  with  the  divine,  but  he  may  also 
identify  himself  with  his  fellowmen.  In  so  far  as  he  '  loves  his 
neighbour  as  himself,'  he  may  be  said  to  have  made  this  identifica- 
tion ;  and,  if  it  be  urged  that  such  love  is  rare,  Jones  at  least 
would  reply  that,  in  the  love  of  a  mother  for  her  child,  it  often 
seems  to  be  fully  realised.  And  I  do  not  think  that  either  Mr. 
Bradley  or  Mr.  Bosanquet  would  deny  this.  But  it  is  perhaps 
true  that  they  tend  to  lay  the  emphasis  rather  strongly  on  the 
finitude  of  the  individual,  especially  in  their  references  to  the 
moral  life,  and  in  their  attitude  to  the  question  of  immortality. 

With  regard  to  the  relation  between  morality  and  religion,  it  is 


346  CBITICAL  NOTICE: 

important  to  remember  that  both  these  terms  are  highly  ambiguous, 
In  primitive  communities  religion  is  apt  to  mean  little  more  than  a 
number  of  ritual  observances,  chiefly  designed  to  avert  the  jealousy 
of  supernatural  powers ;  while  morality  means  the  rules  that  regu- 
late the  actions  of  human  beings  with  reference  to  each  other  and 
to  the  society  to  which  they  belong.  At  such  a  stage  it  can  hardly 
be  doubted  that  morality  is  the  higher  of  the  two.  But  when  re- 
ligion ceases  to  mean  the  dread  of  demons  and  comes  to  mean 
reverence  for  our  highest  ideals,  and  when  morality  ceases  to  mean, 
obedience  to  law  and  comes  to  mean  the  effort  to  realise  our  ideals, 
the  relations  between  them  take  on  a  very  different  character.  Sir 
Henry  Jones  insisted  on  interpreting  both  terms  in  the  highest  sense 
that  can  be  given  to  them  ;  and  his  complaint  against  Mr.  Bradley 
and  Mr.  Bosanquet  is  that  they  tend  to  understand  morality  in  a 
lower  sense,  and  consequently  to  represent  it  as  far  below  what  they 
understand  by  religion,  and  even  as  being  somewhat  antagonistic 
to  it.  This  is  to  some  extent  a  verbal  question.  Jones  refers,  in 
particular  (Lecture  XI.),  to  the  chapter  on  '  The  World  of  Claims 
and  Counter-claims  '  in  Mr.  Bosanquet's  work  on  The  Value  and 
Destiny  of  the  Individual ;  and  of  course  he  agrees  entirely  with 
Mr.  Bosanquet  on  the  unsatisfactoriness  of  such  a  world ;  but  he 
refuses  to  acknowledge  it  as  the  world  within  which  the  moral  life 
of  humanity  is  carried  on.  '  Morality,'  he  says  (p.  164),  '  is  a  con- 
tinuous development  of  mankind's  will  to  good.  It  is  a  growing 
process  :  the  highest  ideal  breaking  out  into  a  succession  of  different 
manifestations  as  mankind  moves  from  stage  to  stage.'  And  he 
urges  that  the  supposed  opposition  between  morality  and  religion 
is  due  to  an  effort  to  '  separate  the  two  aspects  of  spiritual  life,  and 
substantiate  these  aspects  in  their  isolation.  If  the  ideal  is  regarded 
as  real,  the  attitude  of  the  spirit  is  religious  and  super-moral.  If 
the  ideal  is  considered  to  await  attainment,  the  attitude  is  moral 
and  apt  to  be  irreligious  or  merely  secular.  And  inasmuch  as  it  is 
assumed  that  the  ideal  must  be  either  real  or  unreal,  there  is  no  way 
of  avoiding  the  option  between  the  religious  and  the  moral  life. 
How  both  can  be  possible  remains  unexplained  and  a  mystery  in- 
capable of  explanation  from  this  point  of  view.'  His  contention  is 
that  the  antithesis  of  '  real '  and  '  unreal '  is  solved  by  the  concep- 
tion of  progressive  realisation :  and  that  within  this  conception  there 
is  room  for  both  morality  and  religion.  '  Eeligion,  in  the  end,  is  a* 
way  of  life,  and  life  is  perpetual  intercourse  with  temporary  cir- 
cumstance. Nor  was  there  ever  living  morality  not  inspired  by  an 
ideal,  or  a  moral  life  not  in  pursuit  of  what  was  held  to  be  an 
absolute  and  final  good.'  He  was  thus  a  firm  believer  in  the  reality 
of  progress,  both  in  the  individual  life  and  in  the  life  of  humanity. 

Holding  such  views,  he  was  naturally  led  also  to  a  belief  in  human 
immortality — not  of  course  on  the  ground  of  a  claim  for  compensation 
on  account  of  suffering  in  the  present  life,  but  rather  on  the  Kantian 
ground  of  the  demand  for  moral  perfection.  The  following  passage 
gives  the  most  definite  statement  on  the  subject  (p.  347)  :  '  It  is 


SIR  HENRY  JONES,  A  Faith  that  Enquires.         347' 

not  possible  to  maintain  the  limitless  love  and  power  of  God  if  the 
soul  be  not  immortal.  There  are  men,  so  far  as  we  can  see,  wha< 
die  in  their  sins.  If  death  ends  all,  then  their  lives  can  be  called 
nothing  but  failures.  These  persons  have  missed  what  is  best ;, 
they  have  not  used  the  opportunities  of  life  to  build  up  a  good 
character.  The  failure  of  their  lives  is,  so  far  as  they  are  concerned^ 
the  failure  of  God's  purpose.  It  was  not  benevolent,  or  it  was  not 
strong  enough,  to  secure  their  well-being.  And  what  of  those  indi- 
viduals who  have  not  missed  the  purpose  of  their  present  life — but,, 
as  we  would  hold,  have  all  their  lives  morally  "  attained  "  ?  Is  the 
result  of  their  strivings,  failures  and  successes  to  go  for  nothing, 
when  death  comes  ?  To  affirm  this,  it  seems  to  me,  is  impossible 
except  to  those  who  have  not  learnt  to  value  spiritual  achievement^ 
What  remains  for  him  who  thus  gives  up  the  ethical  character  and 
the  universal  ideal  of  the  cosmos  ?  We  have  only  to  ask  the 
question  to  perceive  that  he  who  gives  these  things  up,  gives  up, 
the  conditions  under  which  his  rational  faculties  can  be  of  use. 
And  the  answer  of  the -believer  to  the  unbeliever  is  overwhelming  L 
denial  of  the  immortality  of  the  soul  implies  absolute  Scepticism." 
I  am  not  sure  that  I  quite  understand  what  he  means  by  *  scepticism ' 
here.  I  think  he  means  doubt  with  regard  to  the  possibility  of  a, 
spiritual  interpretation  of  life. 

On  the  exact  nature  of  the  immortality  that  is  thus  postulated,, 
he  does  not  greatly  enlarge  ;  but  two  statements  at  least  are  sig- 
nificant. '  My  assumption  is,  that  the  intercourse  between  man 
and  his  world  will  have  a  character  on  the  other  side  of  death 
similar  to  that  which  it  has  on  this  side  '  (p.  344).  '  God's  good- 
ness being  unlimited,  the  opportunity  not  made  use  of  by  man  in, 
the  present  life  is  renewed  for  him  in  another  life,  and  in  still 
another ;  till,  at  last,  his  spirit  finds  rest  in  the  service  of  the  God. 
of  Love.'  It  seems  clear  from  these  passages  that  the  immortality 
that  he  has  in  view  is  akin  to  that  which  is  at  least  popularly  en- 
tertained in  the  East — successive  reincarnations  till  moral  perfec- 
tion has  been  attained.  What  happens  after  this  attainment  seems 
to  be  left  with  a  similar  vagueness  to  that  which  it  commonly  has 
in  the  Eastern  doctrines.  It  seems  clear,  however,  in  view  of  what 
he  has  stated,  that  he  could  hardly  have  accepted  the  Eastern 
doctrine  of  karma,  at  least  in  the  form  in  which  it  is  usually  ex- 
plained. For,  according  to  such  explanations,  the  doctrine  appears* 
to  rest  on  that  conception  of  '  claims  and  counter-claims,'  which 
he  so  decisively  repudiates.  The  successive  embodiments,  as- 
conceived  by  him,  would  not  be  determined  by  any  reference  to 
rewards  or  punishments  for  previous  actions,  but  purely  by  the 
demand  for  fresh  opportunities  for  moral  growth  and  education. 
This  would  seem  to  imply  a  more  real  persistence  of  human  per- 
sonality than  the  Eastern  sages  are  in  general  prepared  to  admit.. 
A  question  naturally  presents  itself  at  this  point  with  reference  to- 
the  lower  animals.  All  that  Jones  says  on  the  general  problem 
applies  primarily  to  human  life  ;  but,  at  several  points,  he  seems  to. 


348  CEITICAL  NOTICE: 

recognise  that  the  life  of  beasts  is  not  separated  from  humanity  by 
an  impassable  gulf.  He  refers  several  times  to  maternal  love  as 
the  supreme  instance  that  is  known  to  us  of  self-identification  with 
another ;  and  he  recognises  (p.  72)  that  this  form  of  love  is  found 
in  the  lower  animals.  And,  in  another  passage  (p.  102),  he  states 
that  '  the  whole  of  the  confused  and,  so  far  as  we  can  see,  cruel 
history  of  the  struggle  of  beast  with  beast  and  man  with  man  and 
both  with  nature,  must,  somehow,  prove  to  be  at  every  step  the 
.fulfilment  of  a  perfect  will '.  This  appears  to  point  to  the  sugges- 
tion that  animal  souls  also  are  to  be  regarded  as  on  the  road  to 
moral  attainment.  But  this  is  not  explicitly  stated.  Some  might 
even  be  disposed  to  go  farther,  and  enquire  whether  plants  are  to 
be  included,  or  those  sensitive  metals  that  Mr.  J.  C.  Bose  appears 
to  have  discovered.  Once  the  principle  of  individual  persistence 
is  asserted,  it  is  not  easy  to  determine  where  the  line  is  to  be 
'drawn. 

Sir  Henry  Jones  was  not  unaware  that  the  general  doctrine  which 
he  thus  sets  forth  is  beset  by  serious  difficulties,  and  he  admits 
them  with  admirable  candour.  He  notices,  in  particular,  the 
difficulty  that  arises  with  regard  to  the  perfection  of  the  divine 
Being.  His  fundamental  hypothesis  is  that  God  is  a  Being  perfect 
in  wisdom,  power  and  goodness.  But  he  has  been  led  also  to  re- 
gard God  as  immanent  in  the  changing  world.  This  view,  as  he 
•says  (p.  358),  '  involves  the  rejection  of  the  idea  of  God  as  perfect 
in  the  sense  that  He  is  unchangeable.  It  looks  obvious  that  what 
is  perfect  cannot  change  except  for  the  worse.  But  even  were  that 
true,  it  does  not  justify  us  in  saying  that  the  impossibility  of  change 
•or  its  absence  is  either  a  feature  or  a  condition  of  perfection.  It 
is  evidently  a  conception  that  is  totally  inapplicable  to  life  in  every 
form  and  at  every  stage.  Life  is  constant  self -re- creation.  .  .  . 
The  whole  Universe  is  a  single  process ;  and,  if  our  conclusions 
hold,  the  reality  at  the  heart  of  that  process,  which  expresses  itself 
in  it,  and  which  in  truth  it  is,  is  the  Absolute  of  philosophy,  the 
God  of  religion.'  But,  he  adds,  '  it  does  not  seem  easy  to  justify 
the  conception  of  the  Divine  Being  as  moving  from  perfection  to 
perfection.'  Yet  this  is  the  view  to  which  he  gives  his  adhesion. 

It  is  here,  more  than  at  any  other  point,  that  we  see  the  real 
source  of  the  difference  between  the  doctrine  of  Edward  Caird, 
which  Jones  in  substance  adopts,  and  that  of  Mr.  Bradley  and 
Mr.  Bosanquet.  Readers  will  remember  the  emphasis  that  Caird 
laid  upon  the  conception  of  an  ultimate  '  triumph  '  of  the  good,  and 
how  Mr.  Bosanquet  criticised  that  conception.  For  the  latter,  as 
for  Mr.  Bradley,  perfection  is  essentially  timeless ;  and,  so  far  as 
it  can  be  said  to  show  itself  in  time  at  all,  it  must  be  regarded  as 
showing  itself  throughout  its  course.  Caird  and  Jones,  on  the 
other  hand,  regarded  the  time  process  as  a  real  aspect  of  the 
Absolute ;  and  this  seems  to  imply  that  the  end  is  more  perfect 
than  the  beginning.  Perhaps  there  is  a  way  out  of  the  difficulty 
*to  which  Jones  does  not  explicitly  refer.  His  great  hypothesis,  as 


SIB  HENEY  JONES,  A  Faith  that  Enquires.          349' 

we  have  seen,  is  that  God  is  to  be  regarded  as  perfect  in  wisdomr 
in  power,  and  in  goodness.  Each  of  these  terms  seems  to  imply  an: 
outward  reference.  Wisdom  must  mean  insight  into  something, 
power  the  ability  to  do  something,  goodness  the  love  and  support 
of  something.  Hence  the  nature  of  God,  as  thus  conceived,  would 
seem  to  imply,  as  it  does  with  Hegel,  a  process  of  going  out  of 
self  and  returning  into  self.  There  would  be  what  some  have 
described  as  a  '  metaphysical  fall,'  as  well  as  a  moral  rise.  Here 
again  we  may  be  reminded  of  the  Eastern  doctrine  of  alternating 
periods  of  evolution  and  involution  in  the  Cosmos.  From  this 
point  of  view,  God  (or  Brahma)  would  be  only  the  potentiality  of 
the  completed  Cosmos ;  and  it  would  only  be  God  together  with 
his  world  that  could  be  characterised  as  absolutely  perfect.  Or, 
to  put  it  otherwise,  God  would  not  only  be  present  in  the  cosmic 
process,  but  would  also  stand  on  a  Pisgah  height  from  which  that 
process  could  be  surveyed  in  its  completeness,  and  to  which  the 
developing  consciousness  would  eventually  rise.  I  believe  some- 
thing of  this  kind  is  implied  in  Jones's  statements.  Of  course, 
even  this  would  not  solve  the  problem  of  time ;  and,  indeed,  he 
does  not  profess  to  have  solved  that  problem.  On  any  '  idealistic ' 
theory,  it  would  seem  that  the  Absolute  must  be  conceived  as 
highly  complex  and  hard  to  comprehend  in  its  totality ;  and,  as 
we  may  see  from  the  elaborate  work  of  Mr.  Alexander,  this  applies 
to  '  realistic '  theories  as  well.  In  neither  case  can  the  results  be 
summed  up  in  a  few  simple  phrases ;  but,  while  Sir  Henry  Jones 
gives  us  to  understand  that  the  denial  of  personal  immortality 
would  be  fatal  to  his  hypothesis,  Mr.  Alexander  is  hardly  less  ex- 
plicit in  declaring l  that  the  affirmation  of  it  would  be  fatal  to  his. 
Perhaps  these  statements  may  eventually  provide  us  with  the 
means  of  applying  a  crucial  test  to  one  or  other  of  them.  But 
Jones  appears  to  have  attached  no  importance  at  all  to  any  em- 
pirical tests. 

It  is  hardly  necessary  to  call  attention  to  the  excellent — some- 
times brilliant — style  of  exposition  that  is  sustained  throughout 
these  lectures.  The  author's  statements  are,  in  general,  so  trans- 
parently clear  that  it  is  hardly  ever  necessary  to  pause,  even  for  a 
moment,  to  enquire  what  his  real  meaning  is — though  sometimes 
its  remoter  implications  may  remain  a  little  obscure.  He  enforces 
his  views  with  striking  illustrations  and  pungent  phrases,  and 
often  with  very  happy  quotations,  chiefly  from  Browning,  Words- 
worth, and  the  Bible.  And  there  is  a  delightful  optimism  in  his 
outlook  on  the  world  which  it  is  not  easy  to  resist.  This  is  all  the 
more  remarkable  when  it  is  remembered  that  most  of  the  writing 
was  done  at  a  time  when  he  was  suffering  great  pain.  Yet  he 
refers  emphatically  more  than  once  (pp.  72  and  360)  to  '  the 
friendliness  of  the  world  '.  If  he  has  not  solved  all  the  problems 
of  that  world  that  he  loved  so  deeply,  he  has  at  least  heartened  us. 
to  struggle  with  them. 

J.  S.  MACKENZIE. 

1  Space,  Time  and  Deity,  vol.  ii.,  p.  424. 


VII.— NEW  BOOKS. 

"The  Life  and  Philosophy  of  Edward  Caird,  LL.D.,  D.C.L.,  F.B.A.  By 
Sir  HENRY  JONES,  LL.D.,  and  JOHN  HENRY  MUIRHEAD,  LL.D. 
Glasgow  :  Maclehose,  1921.  Pp.  xi,  381. 

'Tnis  book  is  a  worthy  memorial  to  a  man  of  singularly  lofty  character, 
whose  philosophical  achievement,  at  a  remarkable  crisis  in  the  develop- 
ment of  philosophy,  was  of  extraordinary  value  to  the  thinking  world. 
Moreover,  by  the  recent  death  of  Sir  Henry  Jones,  it  acquires  the  interest 
of  a  record,  final  except  for  his  unfinished  Gifford  Lectures,  offered  by 
himself,  of  his  own  thought  and  feeling  in  philosophy ;  so  entirely  was 
he  one  with  his  great  teacher  and  predecessor  in  his  attitude  as  a  man  and 
-as  a  philosopher. 

I  purposely  spoke  of  Caird's  philosophical  achievement  at  a  remarkable 
crisis  in  the  development  of  philosophy.  Great  as  is  the  permanent 
value  of  his  writings,  it  is  difficult,  perhaps,  for  those  who  now  have  the 
opportunity  of  beginning  where  he  left  off,  to  appreciate  the  change  in  the 
philosophical  prospect  effected  by  the  huge  task  of  spadework  which  he 
accomplished  in  his  unhasting  and  unresting  activity.  If  I  were  to  sum- 
marise it  in  three  words,  I  should  say  that,  together  with  two  or  three 
-others,  he  set  philosophy  free. 

To  say  the  very  least  of  them,  these  men  set  the  example  of  taking 
^.philosophy  seriously,  and  of  studying  in  more  schools  than  one.  It  was 
not  that  they  brought  in  an  esoteric  illumination  from  Germany.  It  was 
rather  that  they  set  out  to  abolish  altogether  at  once  the  esoteric  and  the 
insular.  They  determined  to  know  and  to  bring  into  intelligible  con- 
nexion whatever  was  great  in  the  world's  philosophical  tradition  and  in 
4he  life  which  was  its  foundation.  Before  their  ample  and  persistent 
study  Plato  and  Aristotle  received  a  new  significance,  no  less  than  the 
great  English  thinkers  from  Locke  to  Hume  and  Mill,  and  Kant  with  his 
predecessors  as  much  as  his  successors.  The  English-speaking  student  at 
least,  when  he  began  the  study  of  philosophy  in  the  sixties  of  last 
century,  had  to  beat  his  own  path  through  thickets  where  now  there  are 
broad  high  roads. 

And  here  in  a  further  sense  Caird's  work  set  philosophy  free.  Not 
merely  did  he  help  to  let  in  light  and  air,  but  he — not  broke  by  violence 
-nor  cut  as  a  Gordian  knot — but  disentangled  with  long  and  irksome  labour 
— the  only  way  in  which  the  chains  of  the  mind  can  be  unloosed — the  fetters 
which  were  strangling  thought.  With  the  instinct  of  a  heroic  pioneer  he 
made  straight  for  the  centre  of  the  labyrinth,  the  point  where  the  human 
mind  seemed  arrested  by  irresoluble  antagonisms  and  antitheses  that  ad- 
mitted no  movement  towards  unity.  This  point  was  the  philosophy  of 
Kant,  in  which  the  ends  of  the  world,  so  to  speak,  had  come  together 
^upon  the  modern  mind. 

After  Caird  had  in  1877  published  his  first  book  upon  Kant,  by  the 
time  that  he  had  taught  in  Glasgow  for,  say,  five  or  ten  years  from  1866 
-  onwards,  and  finally  after  he  had  published  his  second  Kantian  study — 


NEW  BOOKS.  351 

the  work  of  a  lifetime  for  a  man  of  ordinary  energy — in  1889,  it  was  clear 
in  principle  to  all  men  that  the  barriers  were  down.  The  spiritual  world 
had  taken  its  place  as  simply  the  natural  world  understood  in  the  fullest 
light,  and  within  it  especially  the  moral  life  as  the  natural  life  lived  at 
the  highest  intensity  and  in  the  largest  enlightenment.  If  something 
which  was  not  this  lesson,  but  rather,  as  might  seem,  its  opposite,  ap- 
peared to  be  read  on  the  single  and  several  pages  of  Kant,  that  was  only  a 
case  of  the  common  experience,  that  the  great  interpreter's  insights  are 
apt  to  be  diametrically  opposed  to  the  superficial  reader's  assents. 

It  was  now  clear  that  the  ancient  antitheses  of  a  priori  and  a  posteriori, 
supernatural  and  natural,  the  thing  in  itself  and  the  thing  for  us,  had  lost 
their  obstructive  power  and  reciprocally  exclusive  meaning.  Philosophy 
had  regained  something  of  the  amplitude  and  freedom  which  it  had  pos- 
sessed in  Plato's  day  ;  and  its  field,  no  longer  parcelled  into  fractions, 
revealed  endless  fascination  to  enquirers  in  every  corner  of  its  connected 
whole.  New  groups  of  thinkers,  new  growths  of  thought,  sprang  up  on 
•every  side,  and  none  of  them,  probably,  were  without  a  serious  value. 

The  character  of  this  great  work,  due  to  Caird's  generation,  is  pro- 
claimed in  the  volume  before  us  with  striking  eloquence  and  enthusiasm. 
It  is  right  and  natural  that  the  Life,  which  occupies  the  first  160  pages 
of  the  book  (the  Letters  following  with  80,  and  an  appreciation  of  the 
Philosophy  with  135)  should  lay  stress,  as  it  does,  rather  on  the  teaching 
And  civic  activity  at  Glasgow,  and  the  subsequent  functions  of  the  Master- 
ship of  Balliol,  than  on  the  genesis  of  the  books  on  Kant,  the  influence  of 
which  necessarily  came  later  than  that  of  the  professorial  utterances. 
Yet  a  word  would  have  been  welcome  on  the  personal  aspect  of  these 
works,  with  the  extraordinary  exertion  which  they  demanded.  The  Evolu- 
tion of  Theology  indeed,  is  mentioned  in  connexion  with  the  closing  Ox- 
ford period  ;  otherwise  the  treatises  figure  mainly  in  the  account  of  the 
Philosophy. 

The  Life,  however,  is  a  fascinating  study,  in  its  tone  of  whole-hearted 
love  and  reverence,  representing  with  truth  and  sincerity  the  effect  of 
Caird's  influence  not  merely  on  his  personal  friends,  but  on  the  enormous 
classes  which  passed  through  his  lecture-room  for  the  twenty-seven  years 
of  his  Professorship.  He  had  his  hand,  it  is  said  somewhere  in  the  book, 
on  the  heart  of  Scotland  ;  and  those  of  us  who  remember  what  we  learned 
in  our  friendships  with  his  students  whom  we  knew  at  Balliol,  can  form 
some  idea  of  the  effect  on  Scotland,  and  especially  on  her  churches,  of  this 
continuous  stream  of  awakened  and  enthusiastic  intelligences. 

I  can  only  say  briefly,  what  I  believe  most  of  us  to-day  would  admit,  that 
in  his  political  attitude  and  his  social  activity  Caird,  like  Green,  was 
practically  always  right.  The  chapter  on  the  subject  in  the  Life  is  ex- 
ceedingly convincing  and  full  of  interest  for  social  workers.  His  per- 
sistent and  positive  attitude,  both  in  industrial  matters  and  on  the 
relations  of  women  to  the  University,  though  never  attended  by  noise  or 
controversy,  had  a  greater  influence  than  is  generally  known. 

Of  the  letters,  some  make  up  a  very  charming  private  correspondence 
with  a  lady  singularly  gifted  both  for  friendship  and  for  thought,  while 
some,  addressed  to  Prof.  (Sir  Henry)  Jones,  reveal  Caird's  cautious  and 
modest  attitude  in  approaching  the  work  of  Mr.  F.  H.  Bradley.  With  his 
doubts — or  more  than  doubts — regarding  certain  aspects  of  that  work 
both  Sir  Henry  Jones  and  Prof.  Muirhead  fully  sympathise,  and  the  sub- 
ject is  more  amply  recurred  to  in  the  section  on  Caird's  Philosophy,  where 
some  attempt  is  made  to  estimate  his  relation  to  the  younger  groups  in 
general.  This  is  not  the  place  for  a  discussion.  But  I  hold  myself  bound 
to  suggest  my  own  point  of  view  by  just  referring  to  two  passages  of  Prof. 
Muirhead's  argument.  It  occurs  to  me  that  page  280,  recognising  a  feeling 


352  NEW   BOOKS. 

of  uneasiness  apt  to  be  aroused  rather  by  the  width  of  Caird's  formula? 
than  by  any  want  of  truth  in  them,  indicates  the  need  of  a  further  analysis 
of  experience  than  that  which  the  sequel  of  the  passage  furnishes  ;  and 
that  if  pages  354  and  355  are  to  be  read  as  justifiable  extremes  within  one 
and  the  same  doctrine,  their  union  makes  inevitable  a  fresh  enquiry  into 
the  relative  aspects  of  appearance  and  reality  which  belong  to  the  in- 
dividual. 

Passing  from  this,  I  will  conclude  by  pointing  out  Prof.  Muirhead's 
well-justified  allusion  to  Dr.  McTaggart's  true  and  remarkable  estimate 
of  the  first  set  of  Gifford  Lectures,  those  on  the  Evolution  of  Religion 
(p.  332).  If  the  great  books  on  Kant  may  seem  to-day  to  have  passed 
into  our  foundations,  the  two  sets  of  Gifford  Lectures,  and  especially,  for 
the  ordinary  reader,  these  the  earlier  ones,  are  still  a  delight  and  an 
illumination  to  students  of  religion.  Here  we  have  Caird's  large  and  free 
method  inspired  by  a  crowning  interest,  which  carries  the  reader  forward, 
and  invites  him  to  participate  profoundly  in  the  actual  experience  before 
him.  I  do  not  think  there  is  anything  finer  or  more  attractive  in  the 
literature  of  modern  philosophy. 

BERNARD  BOSANQUET. 


Hellenism    and    Christianity.      By    EDWYN    BEVAN.       London  :    Geo. 
Allen  &  Unwin,  Ltd.,  1921.     Pp.  275. 

Mr.  Bevan's  new  volume  of  essays — most  of  them  have  appeared  before, 
but  a  lover  of  good  literature  will  be  glad  to  have  them  collected — has  all 
the  charms  one  has  come  to  connect  with  his  writing,  graceful  style,  ripe 
and  all-round  scholarship,  a  delicate  controversial  touch,  an  accurate  eye 
for  the  vie  intime  of  the  human  soul,  fine  and  reverent  Christian  spirit. 
It  should  make  a  most  acceptable  work  to  any  one  who  feels  himself,  as 
many  of  us  do  in  these  days,  at  the  parting  of  the  roads,  alive  to  the  high 
probability  that  the  whole  Christian  view  of  life  and  duty  is  on  trial  in  our 
day  as  it  never  has  been  before,  and  anxious  to  make  an  enlightened  choice 
for  the  better  part.  I  do  not  say  that  everyone  who  reads  Mr.  Bevan's 
pages  will  be  induced  to  choose  with  him  for  the  "  reproach  of  the  Cross," 
though  I  have  myself  no  doubt  that  wisdom  lies  on  that  side.  But  at 
any  rate,  Mr.  Bevan's  reader  will  not  be  misled  into  choosing  the  other 
way  by  being  offered  a  caricature  of  the  Christian  alternative, — and  it  is 
often  caricatured  by  ill-informed  well-wishers  no  less  than  by  malicious 
enemies, — or  by  the  childish  pretence  that  the  Christian  interpretation  of 
the  Universe  is  somehow  in  conflict  with  that  ''science  "  for  which  we  are 
nowadays  expected  to  cultivate  an  exaggerated  admiration.  The  first 
four  essays  deal  with  ground  which  Mr.  Bevan  has  very  peculiarly  made 
his  own  as  an  accurate  scholar  in  Hellenistic  history  and  literature.  We 
are  introduced  in  the  Preface  to  a  guiding  thought  of  the  whole  volume. 
What  we  call  our  "civilisation,"  apart  from  certain  ethical  and  religious 
elements  deriving  from  Palestine,  is  a  development,  a  very  recent  and 
rapid  one,  from  the  spirit  of  "  rationalism  "  which  found  its  classic  ex- 
pression in  Greek  philosophy  and  literature  and  art,  and  from  tirs  spirit, 
in  the  sense  of  the  temper  of  critical  intelligence  which  insists  on  "  getting 
the  values  of  things  in  their  true  proportions  "  there  is  no  getting  away. 
The  essay  on  East  and  West  then  raises  the  all-important  question 
whether  the  rationalist  spirit  is  only  an  expression  of  something  peculiar 
to  "  Western  European  humanity  ".  Is  it  true  that  "  East  is  East  and 
West  is  West,"  and  that  there  is  really  nothing  allgemein-menschlich 
about  the  logical  temper  ?  The  question  imperatively  demands  discussion 
no  less  in  view  of  the  recent  recrudescence  of  every  kind  of  uncritical 


NEW  BOOKS.  353 

superstition  among  us  than  in  view  of  the  reckless  and  confident  asser- 
tions of  many  who  have  no  personal  acquaintance  with  the  "  unchanging 
East  "  and  some  few  who  have.  Mr.  Bevan's  essay  puts  very  plainly  some 
of  the  issues  which  the  anti-rationalists  commonly  contrive  to  shirk.  It 
needed  to  be  pointed  out  that  the  inferences  commonly  drawn  from  the 
absorption  of  what  were  once  Hellenistic  and  Christian  communities  in 
Syria  and  Egypt  by  an  apparently  sterile  Mohammedanism  and  the  decay 
of  the  ones  apparently  flourishing  intellectual  culture  of  the  Caliphate 
are  misleading.  The  reminder  is  timely  that  the  facts  in  both  cases  are 
commonly  misinterpreted.  The  populations  which  seem  to  have  lost  the 
*'  Western  "  culture  they  once  had,  are  not,  in  fact,  the  old  populations 
of  the  countries  in  question.  Hellenistic  culture  in  Egypt  and  Syria  did 
not  die  from  want  of  a  suitable  soil  but  went  down  before  conquerors  from 
the  Arabian  deserts  who  had  neither  part  nor  lot  in  it.  And  the  once 
promising  literature  and  science  of  Bagdad,  again,  was  destroyed  by  the 
upheavals  which  sent  out  successive  hordes  of  Mongolian  invaders  from 
Central  Asia.  So  that  the  alleged  facts  of  the  writers  about  the  "  un- 
changing East  "  never  really  happened.  In  the  essays  on  Bacchylides  and 
the  Greek  Anthology,  Mr.  Bevan  is  preparing  the  way  for  the  admirable 
sketch  given  in  the  fourth  paper,  The  First  Contact  of  Christianity  and 
Paganism,  of  the  societies  in  Europe  to  which  the  first  message  of  the 
Gospel  came.  He  rightly  accentuates  the  points  that  Christianity  came 
in  the  first  instance  as  a  great  message  of  hope  to  a  world  absolutely 
crashed  under  the  terrors  of  the  unknown  to  an  extent  we  find  it  hard  to 
realise,  and  that  its  immediate  effect  was  to  offer  men  a  direct  communica- 
tion with  a  benevolent  Ruler  in  place  of  an  elaborate  and  puerile  system 
(if  the  word  may  be  used)  of  magical  compulsions  of  malignant  powers. 
The  extent  to  which  baleful  astrological  superstition  had  enslaved  the 
Hellenistic  world  (as  something  of  the  same  kind  may  not  improbably 
enslave  us  again  if  Christianity  should  lose  its  meaning  for  us),  is 
admirably  illustrated  from  the  "Hermetic  "  writings  by  Mr.  Bevan.  He 
does  not  refer  to  the  literature  of  Neo-Platonism,  but  the  same  thing  may 
be  seen  there.  The  greater  Platonists,  like  Plotinus,  ardently  opposed 
the  "  world-rulers,"  even  as  St.  Paul  did  ;  men  less  firm  in  their  faith,  like 
Porphyry,  took  a  life-time  to  emancipate  themselves  from  their  terrors  ; 
how  low  some  could  sink  may  be  learned  from  a  work  like  the  Letter 
of  Abammon  to  Porphyry  for  which  lamblichus  had  so  long  to  take  a 
discredit  he  did  not  deserve.  The  essay  on  the  Gnostic  Redeemer,  which 
forms  a  pendant  to  that  just  spoken  of,  discusses  in  an  interesting  way  the 
question  whether  the  Scar^p  of  the  Gnostics  is  an  original  feature  of  their 
doctrines  .or  an  attempt  to  graft  a  borrowing  from  Christianity  on  a 
scheme  of  magic  which  really  requires  not  a  "  saviour "  but  a  mere 
revealer  of  spells  and  "words  of  power".  Mr.  Bevan  inclines  to  the 
latter  view,  which  certainly  seems  the  more  logical ;  I  regret  that  I  have 
not  the  knowledge  of  the  history  of  Gnosticism  necessary  for  a  judgment 
on  the  issue.  Two  essays  which  follow  give  us  vivid  and  pleasing 
sketches  of  the  personality  of  the  great  man  who,  next  to  St.  Paul,  has 
done  most  to  stamp  the  impress  of  a  commanding  personality  on  the 
whole  thought  of  Western  Christianity,  St.  Augustine,  "the  first  modern 
man  ".  I  suspect,  though  Mr.  Bevan's  pietas  towards  the  greatest  intellect 
of  the  centuries  when  our  modern  world  was  in  incubation  will  not  allow 
him  to  say  so,  he,  like  myself,  is  by  no  means  of  opinion  that  the  enduring 
influence  of  Augustine  has  been  wholly  for  good. 

In  the  short  essay  on  Dirt  we  have  a  very  happy  attempt  made  with 
true  psychological  insight  to  throw  light  on  the  curious  and  universal 
association  of  the  unclean  and  the  exceptionally  revered  and  holy  under 
the  common  notion  of  "  taboo  ".  I  commend  very  strongly  the  sober  and 

23 


354  NEW   BOOKS. 

judicious  tone  of  the  three  essays  which  deal  specially  with  features  of  the 
Chri  ,tian  conception  of  the  world's  history  which  arouse  a  great  deal  of 
controversy  at  the  present  moment,  those  on  Human  Progress,  Eschatology 
and  Reason  and  Dogma.  If  I  say  no  more  about  these  essays,  it  is  only 
because  I  could  do  nothing  but  express  my  own  warm  sympathy  with 
almost  every  word  of  them.  I  am  particularly  delighted  to  see  that  Mr. 
Bevan  will  not  consent  to  be  "  in  the  fashion  "  by  expunging  belief  in  the 
miraculous,  the  Second  Advent  and  the  presence  of  genuine  prediction  of 
the  future  in  Scripture  from  his  creed.  This  may  damage  him  in  the 
eyes  of  some  uncompromising  "modernists,"  but  I  feel  assured  that  he 
has  the  best  of  the  argument  and  that,  without  any  superfluous  jettison  of 
articles  of  belief,  he  succeeds  in  his  last  essay,  Christianity  in  the  Modern 
World,  in  meeting  the  "rationalist"  (of  the  Rationalist  Press  variety) 
with  as  much  humour  as  logic.  The  germ  of  the  whole  book,  to  my 
mind,  however,  is  the  essay  on  A  Paradox,  of  Christianity  with  its  right 
insistence  that  the  supernatural  hope  is  of  the  very  essence  of  Christianity 
and  that  it  is  lip-service  to  profess  devotion  to  Our  Lord's  conception  of 
human  life  and  duty  when  your  view  of  our  "condition  "  and  destiny  is 
all  the  while  that  of  Epicurus  or  Horace. 

A.  E.  TAYLOR. 

Die  Religionsphilo  sophie  des  Als  Ob,  eine  Nachpriifung  Kants  und  des 
idealistischen  Positivismus.  By  Dr.  HEINRICH  SCHOLZ.  Leipzig  : 
Felix  Meiner,  1921.  Pp.  160. 

More  than  ten  years  ago  I  endeavoured,  by  means  of  an  extended  review 
in  MIND  (No.  81),  to  draw  attention  to  the  importance  of  Vaihinger's 
monumental  survey  of  the  uses  of  fiction  in  our  cognitive  operations,  but 
apparently  neither  my  review  nor  its  own  merits  availed  to  tempt 
English  philosophers  to  undertake  the  800  pages  of  Vaihinger's  great  work. 
In  Germany  its  fate  was  very  different.  It  ran  through  many  editions, 
and  founded  a  school.  *  Idealistic  positivism '  now  has  its  own  Zeitschrift, 
Die  Annalen  der  Philosophie,  in  which  this  valuable  contribution  to  the 
philosophy  of  religion  originally  appeared.  Its  author,  Dr.  Scholz,  is  full 
professor  of  philosophy  at  the  University  of  Kiel  and  an  honorary  D.D.  of 
Berlin,  and  his  work  is  a  very  thorough,  lucid  and  intelligent  criticism  of 
Vaihingor's  religious  philosophy  and  kindred  doctrines. 

Dr.  Scholz  sets  himself  to  examine  Vaihinger's  claims  that  religion  is 
wholly  practical,  and  therefore  does  not  imply  the  real  existence  of  any 
God,  but  only  willingness  to  act  as  if  such  a  being  existed,  and  that  such 
was  the  innermost  meaning  also  of  Kant's  religious  philosophy,  at  least 
in  his  most  lucid  moments.  Coming  from  so  great  an  authority  on  Kant, 
this  contention  naturally  made  a  great  sensation,  which  was  increased  by 
the  copious  documentation  Vaihinger  produced.  Dr.  Scholz  treats  it  very 
seriously.  Incidentally  he  discusses  also  F.  C.  Forberg,  who  actually  held 
the  view  Vaihinger  attributes  to  Kant,  Fichte,  who  did  not,  Reinhold, 
and  others,  who  anticipated  Vaihinger.  To  clear  the  issue,  he  distinguishes 
several  forms  in  which  the  notion  of  '  6ction  '  may  be  applied  to  religion. 
(1)  A  man  may  act  as  if  he  believed  that  God  existed,  though  he  doubts 
it.  (2)  He  may  act  like  a  believer,  though  he  disbelieves.  The  first  is 
called  the  sceptical,  the  second  the  paradoxical  religion  of  the  as-if.  It  is 
however  also  possible  (3)  to  act  as  if  one  knew,  though  one  knows  one 
doesn't.  This  is  not  the  as-i/attitude  proper  but  may  be  called  the  Critical. 
I  may  here  interpolate  that  the  classification  is  not  exhaustive,  because 
one  may  (4)  act  as  if  one  believed  in  order  to  obtain  thereby  evidence  to 
justify  the  belief,  and  that  this  is  the  true  pragmatic  attitude.  Now  ac- 


NEW  BOOKS.  355 

cording  to  Vaihinger  Kant's  deepest  conviction  was  (like  his  own)  the 
second,  while  Dr.  Scholz  holds  that  it  was  the  third,  and  that  religious 
pragmatism  is  a  further  and  valuable  variety.  The  exegetical  struggle  of 
Dr.  Scholz  with  Vaihinger  over  the  body  of  Kant  is  spirited,  and  almost 
Homeric  :  it  leaves  me  with  the  impression  that  both  champions  carry  off 
trophies.  In  other  words,  Kant  is  pulled  to  pieces,  which  is  the  usual 
result  of  coming  to  close  quarters  with  him. 

After  this,  Vaihinger  and  pragmatism  are  compared.  An  accurate  and 
competent  exposition  of  the  religious  bearings  of  pragmatism  arrives  at  the 
conclusion  that  they  are  real  philosophy  and  not  preaching.  Pragmatism 
does  really  overcome  the  conflict  between  faith  and  knowledge,  and  is 
comparable  with  Fichtean  idealism.  It  agrees  with  Vaihinger  (1)  in  its 
radical  empiricism  and  rejection  of  the  speculative  implications  which 
survive  in  Kant.  (2)  Both  agree  with  Kant  that  theoretic  agnosticism  is 
inconclusive.  (3)  In  both  their  philosophy  of  religion  follows  at  once 
from  their  general  principles.  This  is  not  so  in  Kant.  They  differ  in 
that  (4)  The  as-if  doctrine  makes  God's  existence  a  fiction,  while  pragma- 
tism takes  it  seriously.  (5)  Vitally  valuable  judgments  are  as  such  called 
true  by  pragmatism,  but  false  by  Vaihinger. 

Finally  Dr.  Scholz  discusses  whether  either  view  is  really  tenable. 
Vaihinger's  fundamental  notion  of  fiction  is  attacked  with  almost  the 
same  objections  as  were  urged  by  me  in  1912,  and  it  is  shown  (con- 
vincingly) that  knowing  can  be  regarded  as  a  falsification  of  the  real  only 
if  its  true  aim  is  supposed  to  be  'copying  '.  Dr.  Scholz  then  criticises  the 
core  of  pragmatism,  its  notion  of  truth,  and  finds  that  though  it  applies 
well  to  the  truth  of  scientific  theories,  laws  and  synthetic  principles,  it 
fails  to  account  for  logical  and  mathematical  necessities  of  thought,  and 
judgments  of  perception  and  of  history.  It  would  also  include  conven- 
tional and  beneficial  lies  among  truths,  and  so  is  both  (1)  too  narrow,  and 
(2)  too  wide.  (3)  It  fails  to  specify  for  what  truths  are  valuable.  (4)  It 
slurs  over  the  transition  from  empirical  to  moral  verification,  which  is 
wholly  different.  It  is  further  pointed  out  that  moral  and  religious  con- 
victions are  not  merely  tested  by  their  vital  value,  but  to  a  large  extent 
demand  theoretic  justification. 

Hence  Dr.  Scholz  in  the  end  rejects  the  reduction  of  religion  to  a 
practical  attitude  which  is  common  to  pragmatism  and  the  as-if.  Religion 
involves  a  consciousness  of  God  as  the  ens  realissimum,  and  it  is  impossible 
toaffirm  God  in  practice,  while  denying  Him  in  theory.  So  much  for 
Vaihinger.  As  for  pragmatism,  it  has  done  good  service  by  pointing  out 
that  indifference  to  religion  is  not  a  merely  theoretic  attitude  ;  but, 
though  philosophy  can,  religion  cannot,  accept  its  reduction  of  God  to  a 
working  hypothesis. 

I  trust  that  the  above  analysis  makes  it  clear  that  Dr.  Scholz's  argument 
is  not  of  the  gaseous  consistency  so  common  in  religious  philosophy,  but 
furnishes  food  for  reflexion  to  all  who  are  interested  in  religion.  It  dis- 
poses, I  think,  of  Vaihinger  ;  but  not  of  pragmatism.  For  it  is  not  true 
that  the  pragmatic  interpretation  will  not  apply  to  ail  truths. 

(1)  As  regards  the  '  truths  '  of  logic  and  mathematics,  Dr.  Scholz  does 
not  appear  to  have  been  acquainted  with  all  the  relevant  literature.  (2) 
As  for  judgments  of  perception,  it  is  fallacious  to  argue  (p.  140)  that 
their  truth  ihas  to  be  presupposed  by  pragmatism,  because  perceptions 
yield  the  data  to  be  evaluated.  For  it  is  not  admitted  that  truths  of  per- 
ception are  really  '  given '.  Perceptions  are  always  interpretations  of  data 
(which  can  never  be  got  'pure  '),  and  as  such  may  be  true  or  false,  valuable 
or  the  reverse.  (3)  It  is  amazing  that  the  pragmatic  import  of  historical 
judgments  should  be  denied  at  a  time  when  every  nation  is  finding  its 
political  past  a  mill-stone  round  its  neck,  and  denied  by  a  German,  when 


356  NEW  BOOKS. 

the  Versailles  Treaty  and  the  whole  treatment  of  Germany  explicitly  pro- 
fesses to  rest  on  a  belief  about  the  historical  causation  of  the  War.  Dr. 
Scholz's  error  is  however  plainly  due  to  the  common  confusion  of  proposi- 
tions with  judgments.  Whenever  a  historical  proposition  is  turned  into  a 
living  judgment,  it  will  always  be  found  that  its  truth  is  (a)  asserted 
against  an  alternative  version  of  history,  and  (6)  based  on  consequences 
that  are  still  operative  and  verifiable.  (4)  The  difficulties  about  beneficial 
and  conventional  lies  (which  are  only  verbally  lies  at  all)  all  arise  from  the 
ancient  blunder  of  converting  simply  '  all  truths  work '  ;  they  are  easily 
disposed  of  by  distinguishing  the  various  sorts  of  truth-claim  and  the 
parties  involved,  and  by  observing  that  any  lie  works  only  so  long  as  it  is 
taken  as  a  truth.  (5)  If  the  answer  to  the  question  '  for  what  are  truths 
valuable  ? '  is  to  be  stated  in  general  terms,,  it  must  be  '  for  purposes '. 
Anything  more  specific  demands  a  specification  also  of  the  truths.  (6)  It 
may  be  admitted  that  many  religious  doctrines  have  '  theoretic '  implica- 
tions, but  it  does  not  follow  that  these  cannot  be  tested  pragmatically. 
For  just  because  '  theory '  is  essentially  a  means  to  '  practice,'  and  all  our 
activities  are  ultimately  vital,  the  distinction  between  empirical  and  moral 
verification  cannot  be  made  absolute.  Dr.  Scholz  makes  the  further 
mistake  of  supposing  that  because  in  religion  considerations  other  than 
those  of  ordinary  empirical  evidence  and  scientific  reasoning  become 
relevant  and  have  to  be  added,  the  latter  are  to  be  ruled  out.  Whereas 
pragmatism  has  no  reason  to  assume  a  priori  that  religious  hypotheses  are 
incapable  of  verification  in  any  way  that  is  capable  of  engendering  convic- 
tion in  the  human  soul,  or  to  abandon  its  belief  that  "  by  faith  we  may 
also  know  ". 

F.  C.  S.  SCHILLER. 


The  Ethical  Theory  of  Hegel :  a  Study  of  the  Philosophy  of  Right.  By 
HUGH  A.  REYBURN,  Professor  of  Logic  and  Psychology  at  the  Uni- 
versity of  Cape  Town.  Oxford :  at  the  Clarendon  Press,  1921.  Pp. 
xx,  271. 

This  book  was  dedicated  to  Sir  Henry  Jones  by  an  admiring  pupil ;  and 
the  fervent  love  of  the  '  sincere  milk '  of  the  Hegelian  gospel,  by  which 
Jones  was  so  eminently  distinguished,  has  obviously  been,  in  a  high  de- 
gree, communicated  to  his  disciple.  Hegel's  Rechtsphilosophie  has  already 
been  translated  into  English  (though  perhaps  not  quite  satisfactorily)  by 
Mr.  S.  W.  Dyde ;  and  what  Mr.  Reyburn  gives  us  here  is  a  careful  and 
most  instructive  commentary  upon  it,  with  occasional  critical  discussions. 
To  present  any  constituent  part  of  the  philosophy  of  Hegel  in  a  way  that 
makes  it  thoroughly  comprehensible  to  educated  English  readers  is  by  no 
means  easy  ;  and  Mr.  Reyburn  seems  to  me  to  have  carried  out  his  task 
with  a  remarkable  measure  of  success.  He  knows  where  the  difficulties 
lie,  and  he  does  not  shirk  them. 

He  wisely  devotes  a  considerable  part  of  his  book  to  a  general  account 
of  Hegel's  philosophical  attitude  and  method,  explaining,  in  particular, 
the  relations  of  the  Logic  to  the  more  concrete  studies,  the  sense  in  which 
Hegel's  identification  of  the  Real  and  the  Rational  is  to  be  interpreted, 
and  the  place  occupied  by  the  Rechtsphilosophie  in  the  system  as  a  whole. 
He  then  proceeds  to  a  detailed  analysis  of  the  Philosophy  of  Right,  de- 
voting special  attention  to  everything  that  seems  liable  to  misinterpreta- 
tion, supplementing  his  account  by  frequent  references  to  other  writings 
of  Hegel,  and  occasionally,  especially  near  the  end,  calling  attention  to 
what  appear  to  be  inconsistencies  or  defects  in  Hegel's  treatment. 

The  work  is  so  well  done  that  one  is  tempted  to  wish  for  more  ;  and 


NEW  BOOKS.  357 

perhaps  I  cannot  do  better  in  this  review  than  try  to  indicate  some  ways 
in  which  it  might  possibly  be  improved  in  a  future  edition. 

I  suppose  I  ought  not  to  suggest  any  change  of  title ;  but  it  may  at 
least  be  permissible  to  remark  that  '  Theory  of  Ethics  '  is  calculated  to 
convey  a  somewhat  erroneous  impression.  Anyone  who  took  up  the  book 
expecting  to  find  in  it  a  discussion  of  the  topics  commonly  dealt  with  in 
ethical  treatises,  such  as  the  relations  between  desire  and  will,  the  mean- 
ing of  motive  and  intention  and  the  judgments  that  are  passed  on  them, 
the  summum  bonum,  the  duties  and  virtues,  the  methods  of  determining 
what  is  right  (as  distinguished  from  what  are  rights),  would  be  a  good 
deal  disappointed.  Moreover,  the  term  *  ethical '  is  used  in  the  body  of 
the  work  in  a  somewhat  special  sense.  No  doubt  to  call  the  book  '  Theory 
of  the  State  '  would  suggest  too  narrow  a  reference  ;  and  '  Theory  of 
Bights  '  would  be  puzzling.  But  I  do  not  see  why  it  should  not  be  called 
'  Social  Philosophy  '.  All  the  subjects  dealt  with  appear  to  fall  readily 
under  that  designation.  But  no  doubt  the  distinction  between  Ethics 
and  Social  Philosophy  is  a  somewhat  thin  one  ;  and  perhaps  Hegel  would 
not  have  admitted  it. 

Passing  to  the  method  of  treatment,  I  am  inclined  to  agree  with  Mr. 
Reyburn  that  this  part  of  Hegel's  system  is  peculiarly  well  adapted  to 
serve  as  an  introduction  to  his  philosophy — especially  perhaps  for  some- 
what mature  readers  who  have  already  acquired  an  interest  in  legal,  moral, 
and  political  questions.  Hence  he  was  well  advised  in  devoting  a  con- 
siderable part  of  the  book  to  a  general  explanation  of  the  Hegelian  point 
of  view.  But  I  believe  he  might,  with  advantage,  have  done  rather  more 
than  he  has  to  remove  some  of  the  prejudices  that  are  apt  to  be  present 
in  the  minds  of  readers  on  their  first  introduction  to  Hegel — especially 
readers  who  are  already  familiar  with  very  different  methods  of  treatment. 
For  such  readers  it  is  probably  not  enough,  for  example,  to  explain  that 
in  the  statement  that  '  The  Real  is  the  Rational,'  Reality  has  to  be  under- 
stood in  a  special  sense.  What  is  wanted  is  rather  some  concrete  instance 
that  would  make  the  meaning  plain.  I  suggest  that  the  case  of  the  Family 
might  be  taken  as  such  an  instance.  The  normally  permanent  monogamic 
type  seems  clearly  to  be  the  only  one  that  can  be  rationally  defended. 
Now,  many  other  types  have  certainly  existed.  Westermarck's  History, 
which  has  just  appeared  in  an  enlarged  edition,  gives  a  very  full  account 
of  them.  But  what  one  learns  from  reading  such  a  history  is  that  the 
other  types  have  only  had  a  sporadic  existence  at  certain  times  and 
places  in  which  the  circumstances  were  peculiar.  *  What  is  deepest  rooted 
in  nature,'  as  Carlyle  put  it,  is  what  on  the  whole  is  '  found  growing '. 
Instances  of  this  kind  seem  to  me  to  make  Hegel's  meaning  clear  in  a  way 
that  no  definition  of  terms  can  do. 

Again,  readers  of  Hegel  are  apt  to  get  the  impression  that  he  is  need- 
lessly hard — almost  brutal.  He  was  of  course  aware  that  human  life  can- 
not be  altogether  made  into  a  bed  of  roses  ;  and,  like  Carlyle,  he  thought 
it  necessary  to  set  himself  in  opposition  to  certain  forms  of  sentimentality 
that  were  prevalent  in  his  time.  His  emphasis  on  punishment  is  one  of 
the  points  at  which  this  is  apparent.  Now,  some  readers  might  be  apt  to 
think  that,  like  Carlyle,  he  was  in  favour  of  the  treadmill,  or  that  he  would 
have  approved  of  some  of  the  harsh  methods  that  have  prevailed  in  certain. 
English  schools.  To  guard  against  this,  it  should  be  clearly  pointed  out 
that  the  kind  of  punishment  he  has  in  mind  is  that  which  the  offender 
himself  feels  the  need  of  when  he  repents — such  a  punishment,  for  instance, 
as  Dr.  Johnson  inflicted  upon  himself  when  he  stood  bare-headed  at  his 
father's  bookstall  in  Uttoxeter.  His  decisive  condemnation  of  slavery  is 
well  emphasised  by  Mr.  Reyburn  ;  and  here  also  his  attitude  might  be 
contrasted  with  that  of  Carlyle. 


358  NEW  BOOKS. 

Finally,  there  is  a  general  impression  in  many  quarters  that  Hegel's 
theory  of  the  State  laid  the  foundations  of  what  is  now  commonly  referred 
to  as  Prussianism.  Mr.  Bey  burn's  book  was  written  before  the  War  ;  and 
this  ground  of  attack  was  consequently  not  so  much  present  to  his  mind 
as  it  would  have  been  now.  When  a  new  edition  is  called  for,  it  might 
be  well  to  refer  at  some  length  to  this  subject.  It  could,  I  think,  be 
pointed  out  that  Hegel's  approval  of  Prussian  methods  has  been  consider- 
ably exaggerated.  Some  of  his  own  contemporaries  blamed  him  for  the 
half-heartedness  of  his  support.  His  conception  of  the  place  of  the 
monarch  seems  clearly  to  have  been  suggested  by  the  British  constitution 
rather  than  by  the  Prussian.  But,  it  may  be  urged,  did  he  not  at  least 
represent  war  as  a  permanent  necessity,  and  did  he  not  ignore  the  sugges- 
tions that  had  been  already  put  forward  by  Rousseau  and  Kant  for  the 
establishment  of  a  condition  of  lasting  peace  ?  Perhaps  he  ought  to  have 
taken  more  account  of  these.  I  think  Mr.  Reyburn  is  right  in  believing 
that  the  concluding  part  of  the  Rechtsphilosophie  is  the  part  that  is  most 
open  to  criticism.  The  best  defence,  I  suppose,  is  that  Hegel  was,  con- 
trary to  what  is  sometimes  thought,  an  eminently  practical  person.  He 
was  anxious  not  to  give  his  support  to  anything  that  could  not  be  seen  to 
be,  in  Aristotle's  phrase,  rrpaKrov  K.OL  KT^TOV  dv0pa>7r<t>  ;  and  at  the 
time  at  which  he  wrote  he  might  well  have  been  excused  for  thinking  that 
such  proposals  as  those  of  Rousseau  and  Kant  were  Utopian.  But  there 
does  not  seem  to  be  any  ground  for  thinking  that  he  regarded  war  as  in 
itself  a  good,  or  as  a  normal  condition  of  national  life.  He  mentions  it  as 
the  negative  element  that  confronts  the  State  in  the  dialectic  of  history 
and  as  being  essentially  tragic.  We  might  have  expected  him  to  point  to 
a  higher  unity  in  which  the  weakness  of  the  isolated  State  could  be  over- 
come. But  Hegel  declined  the  role  of  prophet.  He  was  a  believer  in 
progress,  as  his  Philosophy  of  History  shows  ;  but  he  was  convinced  that 
the  philosopher,  like  the  owl  of  Minerva,  can  only  venture  to  come  out 
with  his  interpretations  when  the  day's  work  is  over.  This  may  have  been 
a  weakness  in  him  ;  but  at  least  it  would  not  be  easy  to  point  to  any  other 
philosophers  who  have  been  much  more  successful  in  forecasting  the 
future.  He  certainly  did  good  service,  at  a  time  of  considerable  anxiety 
and  serious  dismemberment,  in  emphasising  the  importance  of  a  stable 
and  well  organised  constitution.  I  think  he  had  a  keen  consciousness  of 
the  weakness  that  lay  in  the  somewhat  somnolent  Geuiiithlichkeit  of  his 
native  Wiirtemberg,  and  looked  to  Prussian  energy  as  a  corrective.  Also 
it  should  be  remembered,  as  Mr.  Reyburn  points  out,  'that  if,  in  the 
Rechtsphiloxophie,  which  is  mainly  concerned  with  the  dialectical  evolution 
of  the  State,  he  seems  somewhat  to  overrate  the  importance  of  that  aspect 
of  human  life,  there  are  other  writings  of  Hegel — especially  those  con- 
cerned with  art  and  religion — in  which  he  deals  with  modes  of  experience 
that  transcend  the  limitations  of  the  State. 

Mr.  Reyburn  is  careful  to  state  in  his  Preface  that  the  fellow-workers 
who  assisted  him  are  not  to  be  held  responsible  for  his  '  mistakes  '.  I 
must  confess  that  I  have  not  succeeded  in  detecting  these.  There  is,  in- 
deed, an  unfortunate  slip  in  the  Introduction  (p.  xx),  where  he  says  that 
he  translates  Realitat  by  '  reality  '  :  it  is  by  '  actuality  '  that  he  translates 
it.  There  may  be  other  small  defects  in  the  body  of  the  work  ;  but,  on 
the  whole,  it  may  be  heartily  recommended  to  all  who  desire  to  gain  a 
genuine  insight  into  the  social  and  political  side  of  Hegel's  philosophy  ; 
and,  as  Mr.  Reyburn  is  still  a  comparatively  young  writer,  it  may  not  be 
irrelevant  to  add  that  his  work  gives  promise  of  still  greater  achievements 
in  the  future. 

J.  S.  MACKENZIE. 


NEW  BOOKS.  359 

Self  and  Neighbour.    By  E.  W.  HIRST.    London  :  Macmillan  &  Co.,  Ltd., 
1919.     Pp.  ix,  291.     10s. 

Mr.  Hirst's  book  is  in  every  way  a  competent  piece  of  writing.  He  has 
worked  out  for  himself  a  doctrine  of  the  Moral  Good  ;  and  he  presents  it 
with  a  firmness  and  a  quiet  dignity  that  testify  to  his  belief  .that  his  view 
will  stand,  as  it  has  obviously  sprung  from,  the  criticism  of  reflexion  and 
of  practice.  One  is  a  little  struck  by  the  contrast  between  the  essential 
poise  and  self-possession  of  the  book  and  its  anxiety  to  relate  its  teaching 
at  every  point  to  kindred  doctrines.  Mr.  Hirst  knows  his  own  mind  : 
and  his  book  would  perhaps  have  been  more  direct  and  convincing  if  he 
had  been  less  careful  of  the  opinions  of  others.  But  it  is  a  fault  of  a 
generous  mind  :  and  it  does  not  affect  the  value  of  a  genuine  essay  in 
constructive  ethical  philosophy. 

The  first  part  of  Mr.  Hirst's  book  is  a  critical  historical  survey  of  lead- 
ing types  of  ethical  theory.  His  aim,  it  is  clear,  is  to  show  that  the  defects 
of  these  theories  have  arisen  from  their  failure  to  start  from  and  remain 
within  what  is  to  Mr.  Hirst  the  central  ethical  and  psychological  fact  of 
community.  It  is  easy,  of  course,  to  find  in  at  least  one  main  stream  of 
ethical  thinking,  ample  recognition  of  the  dependence  of  '  ego  '  on  *  alter,' 
and  of  both  on  '  society  '.  But  Mr.  Hirst's  view  is  that  the  relation  has 
not  been  taken  concretely  enough,  and  has  been  constructed  into  some- 
thing other  than  it  actually  is.  Either  the  relation  is  one  obtaining 
between  two  independent  selves,  and  therefore  essentially  secondary — so 
that  the  moral  good  is  stated  in  terms  of  individual  persons  :  or  (more 
rarely)  the  persons  are  mere  terms  of  a  relation,  so  that  the  good  is  not 
'  personal '  in  any  recognisable  sense  of  the  word.  The  first  alternative 
gives  the  varying  forms  of  egoism  and  of  altruism,  and  the  attempt  to  find 
a  satisfactory  mediation  between  them.  The  second  on  which  Mr.  Hirst 
has  less  to  say  in  Part  L,  though  it  is  just  as  relevant  to  his  purpose,  is 
really  the  denial  of  personality  as  a  moral  end  at  all. 

The  criticism  leads  up  to  Mr.  Hirst's  exposition  of  his  own  view.  Es- 
sentially this  is  an  attempt  so  to  interpret  the  doctrine  of  community  as 
to  give  reality  both  to  selves  and  to  the  relation  between  them,  to  hold 
that  while  selves  are  constituted  by  their  relations  to  one  another,  the 
selves  which  are  thus  constituted  are  themselves  real ;  and  their  relations 
are  created  by  their  own  activity.  The  k  good,'  for  Mr.  Hirst,  is  ju^t  this 
'  inter- personal  activity,'  the  good  at  once  ot  a  self  and  of  all  selves,  at 
once  personal  and  social.  "It  is  not  '  good  '  which  is  common,  but  *  com- 
munity '  which  is  good."  It  is  in  this  direct  inter- personal  relationship, 
in  this  activity  for  the  attainment  of  common  ends  that  the  individual 
finds  his  '  good  '  :  and  in  finding  it,  apprehends  that  the  divergence  of  in- 
terest between  '  self  '  and  '  others  '  does  not  exist. 

This  activity  is  not  formal.  It  is  not  a  mere  will  to  good,  but  a  will  to 
achieve  such  ends  as  spring  from  the  reality  of  its  existence.  The  basic 
and  dominating  thing  is  that  in  a  society  of  personalities  living  at  this  full 
stretch  of  common  lifo,  purposes  do  emerge  :  and  if,  on  one  side,  it  is 
these  purposes  which  seem  to  t<ive  content  to  the  common  will,  on  the 
other  hand,  they  are  go<  d  because  they  express  that  will  at  its  fullest. 
The  simplest  and  most  direct  form  of  thi-  inter-personal  activity  is  in 
the  relation  of  parent  to  child  :  and  in  the  purposes  that  spring  from  this 
relation,  there  is  a  type  of  the  working  of  the  good  will  in  every  kind  of 
manifestation.  "  If  it  be  asked,  what  is  the  nature  of  community  as  an 
ethical  principle,  we  can  only  reply  that,  indefinable  as  it  is  i  i  itself,  it  is 
such  a  life  as  a  man  would  live  who  regarded  humanity  as  a  family."  This 
experience,  Mr.  Hirst  insists,  and  the  justification  of  it  as  the  '  moral 
good,'  are  not  to  be  compassed  by  intellectual  means  alone.  "To  be 


360  NEW  BOOKS. 

fully  known,  it  mast  be  experienced.  .  .  .  It  is  not  describable  in  merely 
intellectual  terms  :  for  it  is  a  form  of  the  life  of  the  self  as  a  whole,  and 
is  illustrated  in  the  unity  felt  by  the  members  of  a  family." 

Mr.  Hirst  adds  several  interesting  chapters  on  the  theoretical  and 
practical  implications  of  his  doctrine.  I  should  like  especially  to  draw 
attention  to  his  treatment  of  the  relation  of  metaphysics  and  ethics.  But 
the  critical  question  for  his  book  is  as  to  how  far  he  has  succeeded  in 
making  this  conception  of  the  good  as  inter-personal  activity  at  once  con- 
sistent and  concrete.  It  is  a  difficult  position  to  state :  the  matter  of 
emphasis  is  so  all-important.  But  Mr.  Hirst  certainly  seems  to  me  to 
have  done  considerable  service  in  the  mere  stating  of  the  problem,  and  to 
have  given  a  persuasive  defence  of  his  general  thesis.  He  might,  perhaps, 
since  the  point  is  so  very  central  to  his  position,  have  elucidated  more 
fully  the  process  by  which  he  conceives  that  the  ends  which  are  sought  in 
the  primary  form  of  the  family  so  expand  that  they  require  for  their 
achievement  a  wider  community  of  life  inspired  by  the  same  inter- 
personal activity.  But  the  principle  of  the  deduction  is  clear  enough  : 
and  Mr.  Hirst  may  fairly  claim  to  have  shown  the  possibility  of  basing 
an  ethical  theory  on  a  consideration  of  the  concrete  relationships  within 
which  selves  maintain  themselves  and  discover  their  own  nature. 

H.  J.  W.  H. 

Evolutionary  Naturalism.      By  ROY  WOOD  SELLARS.     Chicago  :   Open 
Court  Publishing  Company,  1922.     Pp.  xiii,  343. 

Mr.  Sellars  has  written  a  book  notable  in  the  kind  to  which  we  have  now 
become  accustomed  from  the  producing  generation  of  American  philo- 
sophers. It  is  an  industrious  contribution  to  the  coming  "  final "  system 
of  Evolutionary  Naturalism.  Starting  with  an  exposition  of  the  theory  of 
knowledge  known  as  Critical  Realism,  Mr.  Sellars  ploughs  remorselessly 
through  ten  chapters  of  category-genetics,  and  attains  the  crux  of  his 
system  in  the  penultimate  chapter  on  the  Mind-Body  problem. 

All  the  modern  discussions  are  familiar  to  our  author,  more  so,  perhaps, 
than  the  older  philosophies,  for  he  shows  a  keen  anxiety  to  be  on  the 
crest  of  the  incoming  wave  ;  and  he  has  obviously  been  influenced  by 
"the  truth"  in  all  these  vain  attempts,  and  has  dexterously  eliminated 
the  falsity,  and  "  by  stepping  warily  and  using  distinctions  "  (p.  194)  has 
welded  the  whole  together  into  a  world-view  in  harmony  with  the  conclu- 
sions of  science,  and  largely  content  with  those  conclusions.  In  a  phrase, 
he  offers  a  view  of  nature  as  a  self-explanatory,  self-sufficient,  self-creat- 
ing, physical  reality,  as  opposed  to  a  "  dead-level  "  mechanical  naturalism. 
And  if  as  against  mechanism  he  cites  "  creative  synthesis,"  even  more 
pointedly  as  against  supernaturalism  he  offers  evolution  and  the  genetic 
method.  His  is  a  naturalism  which  does  not  level  down,  and  if  it  does 
not,  as  idealism  does,  level  up,  at  least  it  faces  facts  such  as  the  appear- 
ance of  the  new  quality  of  life  in  organic  systems,  and  more  important 
still,  that  crucial  instance  of  such  novelty,  the  conscious  experience  of 
man  which  emerges  from,  and  in  turn  guides,  his  living  body. 

Into  the  details  of  Critical  Realism  I  cannot  enter,  but  I  must  indicate 
its  main  results  as  they  affect  the  present  speculation.  The  fundamental 
thing  is  the  distinction  between  subjective  contents  and  objects  known, 
which  corresponds  more  or  less  with  the  distinction  of  two  kinds  of 
knowledge  :  awareness  of  contents  and  knowledge-about  objects.  At  the 
same  time,  contents  are  objects  of  awareness  ;  they  are  subjective  only  be- 
cause they  are  "  intra-organic  responses  to  stimulation  of  sense  organs  " 
(p.  26).  Mr.  Sellars'  use  of  the  terms  content,  object,  and  thing  is  very 


NEW  BOOKS.  361 

perplexing,  but  I  gather  that  the  term  content  covers  not  only  sense-data 
but  also  the  phenomenal  objects  of  perception,  as  well  as  propositions  ; 
everything,  in  fact,  except  physical  things  (and  perhaps  other  minds). 
The  phenomenal  object,  although  it  is  not  a  thing,  is  more  than  mere 
passive  sensuous  content ;  it  involves  judgment,  and  is  the  synthetic  unity 
of  sense-datum  and  meaning,  dominated  by  the  "  sense  of  thinghood"  (p. 
26).  The  plain  man  mistakes  this  object-content  for  a  thing  and  is  thus 
guilty  of  Naive  Realism  ;  the  Idealist  makes  the  converse  blunder.  But 
the  Critical  Realist  knows  that  the  physical  thing  is  not  the  object  of  per- 
ception, and  is  not  given  to  awareness.  Nevertheless  we  may  know  about 
it,  and  that  knowledge  is  the  result  of  inference  from  the  patterned  and 
continuous  data  (p.  190),  which  are  already  adaptive  responses  to  the 
things  which  cause  them.  In  perception  we  "clothe  the  object"  (p.  34) 
in  the  sensuous  content,  but  in  knowledge-about  we  use  the  content  as 
material  for  analysis  and  construction.  And  what  do  we  know  about 
physical  things  ?  We  know  that  they  are  orderly,  massive,  and  executive 
(p.  15),  have  comparative  size  and  position,  structure,  texture,  consti- 
tuents, relations  ;  that  they  change,  behave,  and  have  capacities  of  vari- 
ous kinds  (pp.  35,  42). 

This  is  not  the  place  for  detailed  criticism  of  such  a  theory,  but  those 
who  are  interested  in  the  matter  will  find  that  Mr.  Sellars  is  really  in 
difficulties  because  he  has  not  realised  (or  remembered)  that  the  distinc- 
tion between  awareness  and  knowledge-about  is  not  at  all  identical  with 
that  drawn  by  Mr.  Alexander  between  enjoyment  and  contemplation. 

However  that  may  be,  it  is  upon  his  epistemological  distinctions  that 
Mr.  Sellars  bases  his  solution  of  the  Mind-Body  problem.  That  solution 
is  that  mind  is  a  "physical  category"  (p.  299),  that  consciousness  is  a 
"natural  ingredient  of  functioning  cortical  systems"  (p.  294),  and  that 
the  reason  why  we  cannot  grasp  the  connexion  is  that  while  we  have 
knowledge-about  the  organism,  we  have  immediate  awareness  of  conscious- 
ness itself.  Now  that  is  undoubtedly  ingenious  and  contains  a  profound 
truth.  Nevertheless,  however  we  might  be  prepared  to  allow  that  a  dis- 
tinction of  enjoyment  and  contemplation  would  conceal  the  actual 
emergence  of  enjoyed  consciousness  from  contemplated  cortical  pro- 
cesses, there  is  certainly  no  reason  to  suppose  that  it  must  conceal  the 
secretion  of  the  objective  contents  of  awareness.  If  that  process  is  not 
clear  it  is  simply  because  it  is  secret  and  occult,  or,  as  I  should  suggest, 
highly  speculative. 

It  is  from  this  notion  of  Creative  Synthesis  that  Evolutionary  Natural- 
ism proceeds.  Mr.  Seliars  lays  stress  on  the  development  of  biological 
science  as  tending  to  undermine  the  earlier  "dead-level"  naturalism. 
Even  inorganic  matter  is  active,  subtle,  and  responsive  ;  it  lends  itself  to 
"  mobile  integrations  which  under  the  hand  of  time  may  lead  to  tremend- 
ous novelties  "  (p.  263).  Creative  synthesis  means  "  the  frank  admission 
of  novelty  without  an  appeal  to  a  superphysical  agent  "  (p.  297).  Now, 
however  valuable  that  notion  may  be  for  scientific  methodology,  it  is  not 
philosophically  satisfying.  There  is  all  the  difference  in  the  world  be- 
tween explaining  a  difficulty  and  getting  used  to  it.  Philosophy  must  do 
more  than  "  reflect  the  contemporary  drift "  (p.  298).  What  are  the  im- 
plications and  limits  of  creative  synthesis  ?  I  suggest  these  problems  as 
worthy  of  Mr.  Sellars'  earnest  consideration.  I  do  not  say  that  they 
would  lead  him  further  than  he  is  prepared  to  go,  but  they  would 
certainly  lead  him  further  than  he  has  gone.  Nor  would  his  journey  neces- 
sarily be  in  the  direction  of  a  vicious  supernaturalism  ;  rather  the  contrary  : 
it  was  not  a  good  naturalistic  explanation  which  was  offered  by  the  first 
High  Priest,  that  having  cast  gold  into  the  fire,  "there  came  out  this  calf  ". 

H.  F.  HALLETT 


362  NEW  BOOKS. 

An  Analysis  of  Certain  Theories  of  Truth.  By  GEORGE  BOAS.  University 
of  California  Publications  in  Philosophy,  Vol.  v.,  No.  6.  Berkeley, 
Cal.,  1921.  Pp.  187-290. 

The  University  of  California  has  long  distinguished  itself  by  the  abundance 
and  quality  of  its  philosophic  publications,  and  the  above  study  takes  high 
rank  among  its  productions.  It  is  well  argued  and  well  written  and  makes 
a  real  contribution  to  its  subject.  Dr.  Boas  starts  by  pointing  out  that 
theories  of  truth  have  the  peculiarity  of  forming  part  of  their  own  subject 
matter,  i.e.,  of  being  themselves  cases  of  the  'truth  '  they  set  themselves 
to  define.  Hence  any  definition  of  truth  that  is  adopted  must  (1)  be  true 
of  the  definition  itself.  This  he  calls  being  self-critical.  (2)  That  it  may 
not  begin  by  begging  the  question,  it  must  be  general,  i.e.,  must  not  pre- 
suppose any  specific  metaphysic  or  psychology  or  epistemology.  (3)  It 
must  produce  a  tenable  account  of  falsity.  (4)  It  must  be  applicable. 
He  then  proceeds  to  examine  how  far  the  current  theories  meet  these  re- 
quirements. 

(a)  The  first  of  these  he  calls  Logical  Hedonism  and  regards  as  very 
common.  This  insists  that  truths  must  please,  and  are  adopted  because 
of  the  'emotional  thrill'  they  give.  It  is  itself  pleasing,  and  so  f self- 
critical  '.  It  is  relativistic  indeed,  being  relative  both  to  those  it  pleases, 
and  as  yielding  no  absolute  truth  :  but  this  does  not  damn  it.  For  by 
its  own  criterion  a  theory  could  become  absolute  only  by  pleasing  every 
soul  or  an  absolute  soul  (the  latter  only  if  it  were  absolutely  the  only 
soul  !).  It  is  also  'general,'  and  accounts  for  falsity,  by  reducing  it  to- 
discomfort.  But  it  is  not  applicable  to  all  cases.  We  cannot  decide  by 
its  means  whether  Caesar  crossed  the  Rubicon  in  A.D.  1493  or  in  625  B.C.,  if 
we  don't  care  when  he  did. 

(6)  Truth  as  the  irresistible  is  also  subjectivistie.  What  cannot  be 
denied  and  must  be  believed,  is  true.  This  theory  is  not  'self-critical '. 
For  if  it  were,  it  would  be  universally  adopted  the  moment  it  was  heard. 
Nor  is  it  general,  for  it  demands  a  passive  subject.  It  has  no  criterion  of 
falsity;  nor  applicability,  because  it  cannot  say  when  psychological  im- 
pressiveness  passes  into  logical  irresistibility. 

(c)  The  '  correspondence  '  theory  has  suffered  from  ' '  the  obscurity  of  the 
obvious"  and  was  never  stated  fully.     Now,  it  is  never  stated  openly. 
Here  the  initial  difficulty  is  its  inapplicability.     We  have  no  means  of 
knowing  whether  the  correspondence  with  '  fact '   in  which  the  theory 
consists,  exists  in  fact.     For  this  same  reason  it  cannot  be  declared  '  self- 
critical'.     It  accounts   indeed  for  falsity  as   correspondence  with   non- 
existent fact ;  "  but  to  what  do  meaningless  propositions  correspond  ? " 
Or  practical  ?     In  some  forms,  however,  it  appears  to  be  *  general '. 

(d)  Formal  consistency,  or  lack  of  contradiction,  may  be  taken  as  assur- 
ance of  truth.     This  makes  truth  systematic,  but  does  not  apply  to  the 
postulates  on  which  the  consistent  systems  rest.     Also  a  system  may  be 
consistent  and  false.     In  fact  two  false,  or  one  true  and  one  false,  proposi- 
tions may  be  consistent,  and  two  false,  or  two  true,  propositions,  incon- 
sistent (e.g.,  if  they  belong  to  different  geometries).     So  the  theory  is  not 
1  self-critical '.     It  is  'general '  enough,  but  can  recognise  falsity  only  in  a 
few  self-refuting  propositions.     It  cannot  be  applied,  because  a  contradic- 
tion only  tells  us  that  something  is  wrong,  not  what  is  right. 

(e)  Can  truth  be  made  consistent  and  absolute  in  one  total  truth  and 
the  coherence  of  the  one  significant  Whole  be  The  Truth  ?     Such  truth 
would  be  reality,  and  human  truth  pales  into  insignificance  beside  it. 
However  "the  theory  is  not  self-critical.     For  if  truth  is  the  whole,  state- 
ments about  truth  are  not  true  "  (p.  248).     They  cannot  be  more  than 
partly  true.     So  absolutism  also,  of  which  the  theory  asserts  the  truth,. 


NEW  BOOKS  36$ 

has  only  partial  truth,  and  there's  no  knowing  how  far  it  is  true.  Even 
the  absolutist  moreover  must  admit  that  the  Whole  is  not  wholly  true, 
but  includes  some  falsity,  e.g.,  'Absolutism  is  false'.  Ergo  it  is  either 
true  that  absolutism  is  false,  or  else  it  is  not  the  whole  of  truth.  Further, 
absolutism  is  not  '  general '.  It  requires  a  specific  metaphysic,  theory 
of  judgment  and  logic  of  (internal)  relation.  It  seems,  however,  to  ac- 
count for  falsity.  Falsity  means  the  claim  of  a  partial  judgment  to  be 
true.  But  as  all  judgments  are  partial  and  all  claim  truth,  what  follows, 
is  (1)  that  all  are  false,  and  (2)  that  only  absolutists  err.  The  former  con- 
sequence might  be  welcome,  though  it  would  not  tell  us  what  made  them- 
false  nor  what  the  distinction  between  *  true  '  and  '  false '  could  mean. 
The  latter  means  that  the  absolutist  alone  can  be  aware  that  the  truth- 
claims  he  makes  are  false.  His  adversaries  would  not  make  them,  if  they 
thought  them  false.  Lastly,  the  truth  that  all  partial  truths  are  only- 
par  tly  true  cannot  be  applied  to  determine  how  true  they  are. 

(/)  There  remain  only  the  voluntarists.  For  them  truth  arises  out  of 
the  interpretation  of  signs.  Such  interpretation  is  purposive  and  experi- 
mental, and  continues  till  the  impelling  interest  is  satisfied.  Now  thi& 
theory  is  plainly  '  self-critical ' ;  it  is  willing  to  be  tested  by  its  working. 
It  is  also  general  enough,  though  it  implies  an  activist  epistemology. 
Error  it  explains  as  the  '  anti-truth  '  which  defeats  it.  Its  applicability  is. 
assured,  because  it  is  built  for  application,  and  lets  verification  determine 
verity. 

I  trust  that  the  necessity  of  compression  has  not  entirely  obscured  the 
dialectical  brilliancy  of  Dr.  Boas's  argument,  which  calls  for  criticism  on 
one  point  only.  Dr.  Boas  at  times  substitutes  a  proposition  for  a  real 
judgment,  as  formal  logic  teaches  its  students  to  do.  This  is  why  he  dis- 
misses Logical  Hedonism  for  failing  to  get  any  pleasure  out  of  '  Csesar 
crossed  the  Rubicon  in  A.D.  1493'  :  he  has  failed  to  notice  that  this  is  a. 
paper  '  judgment '  or  mere  proposition,  until  it  has  been  put  in  a  context 
in  which  it  is  really  asserted  and  its  truth  or  falsity  matters.  The 
moment  this  is  done,  its  emotional  value  will  appear.  Thus  the  'hedon- 
istic' theory  will  satisfy  the  four  tests  as  well  as  the  voluntaristic— a  result 
foreshadowed  by  the  fact  that  it  often  fuses  with  ife  into  the  conception 
of  truth  as  the  satisfaction  of  a  purpose,  and  by  the  common  charge  that 
for  a  voluntarist  truth  is  whatever  he  wishes  to  believe.  So  far  from  ad- 
mitting, however,  that  "  if  *  true '  is  defined  as  '  agreeable '  the  two  terms 
ought  to  be  equivalent"  (p.  193),  Dr.  Boas  should  have  pointed  out 
that  the  demand  that  truth  should  be  desirable,  satisfactory  or  agreeable,, 
could  not  be  converted  into  'anything  agreeable  is  true '.  It  cannot  mean 
more  than  that  it  is  a  species  of  the  agreeable,  and  if  so  its  differentia  must 
be  stated.  '  Logical  hedonism  '  would  thereby  transform  itself  into  the  in- 
nocuous theory  that  truth  was  the  pleasure  or  value  arising  from  the  satis- 
faction of  a  cognitive  purpose.  Which  would  be  quite  a  good  definition  for 
human  purposes. 

F.  C.  S.  SCHILLER. 

Fichte  et  son  Temps.    Vol.  I.    By  XAVIER  LEON.    Paris  :  Armand  Colin,, 
1922.     Pp.  xvi  +  649. 

M.  Leon  has  planned  his  work  on  a  magnificent  scale.  In  this  volume  he- 
deals  only  with  Fichte's  life  till  the  departure  from  Jena  at  the  age  of 
thirty-seven.  Two  more  volumes  will  be  required  to  complete  his  task. 
So  large  a  book  enters  naturally  into  much  detail.  But  M.  Leon  never 
allows  the  details  to  obscure  the  main  outlines.  In  spite  of  the  trees  we- 
can  always  see  the  wood,  and  this  is  the  highest  praise  that  can  be  given 
to  the  author  of  a  biography. 


364  NEW  BOOKS. 

As  long  ago  as  1902  M.  Leon  published  a  work  on  the  philosophy  of 
Fichte  which  gave  a  most  full  and  admirable  account  of  it.  In  the  present 
Tolume,  in  consequence,  there  is  no,  very  long  exposition  of  the  works 
published  by  Fichte  in  the  period  under  consideration.  It  is  his  life,  and 
the  influences  which  affected  him,  of  which  we  learn. 

There  are  three  things  which  are  brought  out  very  clearly  in  this 
volume.  The  first  is  that  the  ardent  belief  in  the  virtues  and  destiny  of  the 
German  nation  which  is  so  marked  in  his  later  life  was  absent  in  his  earlier 
years.  He  then  looked  to  France  for  the  salvation  of  the  world  (Fichte, 
unlike  Hegel,  was  always  convinced  that  the  world  was  in  a  bad  way,  and 
required  salvation  very  urgently).  As  late  as  1799,  he  contemplated  re- 
moving to  the  University  of  Maintz,  which  was  just  then  in  French  territory, 
and  hoped  to  be  followed  by  many  of  his  colleagues  and  pupils.  It  was 
not  till  the  establishment  of  the  Empire  that  he  decided  that  France  was 
not  the  destined  saviour  of  the  world,  and  that  Germany  was.  This 
change  of  opinion  took  place  later  than  the  period  dealt  with  in  this 
volume,  but  it  is  sketched  very  effectively  by  M.  Leon  in  his  Introduction. 

The  second  point  which  becomes  clear  from  M.  Leon's  book  is  the 
tremendous  position  which  Fichte  held  in  Germany  in  1799.  No  such 
position  had  then  been  held  by  so  young  a  man  since  the  beginning  of 
modern  philosophy.  Berkeley  and  Hume,  indeed,  had  published  their 
greatest  works  when  they  were  twenty-five  and  twenty-eight.  But  the 
Principles  of  Knowledge  was  only  read  by  Berkeley's  contemporaries  to 
be  laughed  at,  and  the  Treatise  on  Human  Nature  was  not  read  by 
Hume's  contemporaries  at  all.  At  thirty -seven  Fichte  was  acclaimed  as 
the  thinker  who  had  succeeded  and  had  surpassed  Kant.  He  was  the 
leading  philosopher  in  a  nation  which  was  more  interested  in  philosophy 
than  in  any  other  subject. 

Then  came  the  accusation  of  atheism  and  his  dismissal.  M.  Leon's 
account  of  this  is  full  of  interest.  There  cannot  be  the  least  doubt  that, 
in  any  ordinary  sense  of  the  word,  Fichte  was  at  this  time  as  much  an 
atheist  as  Spinoza.  "To  believe  in  God" — so  M.  Leon  sums  up 
Fichte's  position — "  is  not  to  affirm  the  existence  of  some  unknown, 
mysterious,  and  incomprehensible  being  ;  it  is  to  act  conformably  to 
duty  "  (p.  519).  Fichte  was  accused  of  atheism  in  the  ordinary  sense  of 
the  word,  and  it  is  no  answer  to  the  accusation  to  say  that  he  was  not  an 
atheist  in  a  sense  of  the  word  which  had  been  invented  by  himself.  The 
question  was  whether  he  should  be  allowed  to  teach  what  is  ordinarily 
called  atheism. 

There  was  only  one  answer  to  that  question  in  1799  for  a  small 
German  state  which  was  badly  frightened  by  the  French  Revolution.  The 
administration  of  Weimar,  indeed,  would  probably  have  been  content  if 
Fichte  had  agreed  not  to  teach  the  condemned  doctrines,  and  would  have 
allowed  him  to  keep  his  chair.  Kant  had  agreed  to  this  course  in  con- 
nexion with  his  Religion  within  the  Limits  of  Mere  Reason,  but  that  was 
only  an  appendix  to  Kant's  philosophy,  while  Fichte's  philosophy  centred 
round  his  doctrine  as  to  God. 

It  would  probably  have  been  impossible  for  Fichte  to  keep  his  chair  in 
any  case,  and  the  unfortunate  letter  to  Voigt  rendered  the  matter  hopeless. 
"  I  would  have  dismissed  my  own  son,"  Goethe  wrote,  "  if  he  had  allowed 
himself  such  language  in  relation  to  a  government."  Goethe  was  not  only 
Goethe,  he  was  a  German  official  of  1799.  But  it  may  be  doubted  whether 
any  University,  in  any  period,  would  have  retained  a  Professor  who  had 
written  such  a  letter.  Fichte  himself,  while  maintaining  that  he  was  per- 
fectly right,  admitted  that  the  Weimar  authorities  could  not,  from  their 
standpoint,  have  acted  otherwise  (p.  620). 

The  author  hopes  to  publish  the  remaining  volumes  in  1923  and  1924. 


NEW   BOOKS.  365 

They  will  be  expected  with  impatience  by  every  student  of  the  gi eat  days 
of  German  Idealism. 

J.  ELLIS  M'TAGGART. 


Lotze's  Theory  of  Reality.  By  E.  E.  THOMAS,  M.A.,  Late  Fellow  of  the 
University  of  Wales.  London:  Longmans,  Green  &  Co.,  1921.. 
Pp.  1,  217. 

Lotze's  theory  of  thought,  our  author  says,  '  has  already  been  adequately 
dealt  with  by  Sir  Henry  Jones/  and  Mr.  Thomas  therefore  restricts  him- 
self to  Lotze's  theory  of  reality.  Indeed,  he  completes  Sir  Henry  Jones's 
original  project ;  for  the  preface  to  Sir  Henry  Jones's  book  promised  a 
companion  volume  on  precisely  the  subject  of  this  one,  and  as  Sir  Henry 
apparently  abandoned  his  design  long  before  his  lamented  death,  he  left 
the  field  clear  for  another  author  (may  we  say  for  another  Welshman  ?)  to 
continue  what  he  had  begun. 

On  the  other  hand,  this  state  of  affairs  is  perhaps  unfortunate  for  the 
younger  author.  Comparisons  are  scarcely  avoidable,  and  there  is  nothing 
in  the  present  book  to  match  Sir  Henry  Jones's  brilliant  introductory 
chapter  on  *  The  main  problem  of  Lotze's  philosophy '.  Mr.  Thomas,  it 
is  true,  deals  in  part  with  the  same  general  subject  in  his  introduction 
(which  is  largely  historical)  and  in  his  concluding  chapter  (on  '  Lotze's 
achievement  and  influence ')  ;  but  although  he  says  the  right  things,  he 
always  says  them  tamely,  and  anyone  who  requires  an  introduction  to 
Lotze  (and  is  not  familiar  with  Sir  Henry  Jones's  book)  will  find  it  very 
hard  to  infer  from  this  one  why  Lotze  asked  himself  the  questions  that  he 
did  ask,  why  he  reasoned  as  he  did,  and  what  manner  of  man  he  was. 
Lotze's  Stoff-Hunger,  his  zeal  for  the  ordinary  consciousness  ;  his  conse- 
quent attempt  to  clip  the  wings  of  Hegelian  idealism,  on  the  one  hand, 
and  of  scientific  naturalism  on  the  other  hand,  and  the  other  aims  which 
Sir  Henry  Jones  portrayed  so  vividly,  are  treated  here  as  if  they  were 
dead  issues  to  be  set  down,  conscientiously,  in  tolerable  order. 

Mr.  Thomas,  indeed,  has  so  little  sympathy  with  Lotze's  Stoff-Hunger 
that  he  passes  over  the  whole  of  the  second  book  of  the  Metaphysics — the 
Cosmology — in  his  detailed  exposition.  On  the  other  hand,  his  first  six 
chapters  make  a  fair  attempt  to  deal  with  the  first  Book,  and  the  eighth 
and  ninth  begin  the  discussion  of  Book  III.  (Psychology),  although  they 
turn  very  quickly  to  the  treatment  in  the  Microcosmus.  Two  chapters  on 
the  metaphysical  import  of  the  Logic  come  next,  and  Lotze's  suggestion  at 
the  end  of  the  Metaphysics  introduces  a  chapter  on  "Moral  Values  as  de- 
termining the  nature  of  reality  ".  The  seventh  chapter  ('The  passage  to 
the  human  soul ')  gives  no  references  except  two  (on  the  same  page)  to  a, 
section  of  the  Microcosmus. 

In  view  of  Lotze's  lengthy  and  involved  philosophising  it  was,  perhaps^ 
inevitable  that  Mr.  Thomas  should  circumscribe  his  discussion  somewhat 
in  the  above  fashion.  Certainly,  two  of  the  main  contentions  of  Lotze's 
general  metaphysic — the  attempt  to  prove  that  things  are  selves,  and  the 
place  assigned  to  M— are  fully  discussed  in  this  volume,  and  Lotze's  third 
main  contention — his  doctrine  of  relations — is  treated  (although  inade- 
quately) at  some  length.  On  the  other  hand,  the  reader  would  be  helped 
if  the  references  were  fuller,  and  if  something  of  what  is  omitted  were  in- 
dicated in  footnotes  at  least. 

If  the  discussion  is  never  very  lively,  it  is  always  patient  and  pains- 
taking. Mr.  Thomas  does  not  obtrude  his  own  standpoint ;  he  has  no  axe 
to  grind  ;  and  he  deserves  all  the  praise  which  is  due  to  these  estimable 
qualities.  Per  contra,  his  book  would  have  been  far  better  if  he  had 


-366  NEW  BOOKS. 

treated  the  English  language  with  reasonable  respect.     The  word  *  data ' 
is  not  singular  (p.  195)  ;  there  is  no  excuse  for  speaking  of  'structional ' 


startle'  (p.  34)  or  of  'approximating'  one  thing  to  another  (p.  115). 
Among  a  host  of  sentences  which  might  have  been  better  put,  I  cite  the 
following  :  "Thus  the  fact  of  the  existence  of  bodily  sensations,  and  also 
the  fact  that  there  is  a  changing  individuality  of  experienced  sense  con- 
tent different  from  the  permanent  individuality  of  sense  content  as  going 
to  the  constitution  of  an  objective  world,  go  to  show  the  existence  of  a  soul 
life  which  is  exclusive  of,  and  which  stands  over  against  the  world  of  ob- 
jects "  (p.  93). 

"  Lotze"  is  printed  "Lotz"  on  pp.  xlii  and  xliv,  and  the  reference  to 
Met.,  sec.  329  (p.  105  n.),  should  be  to  sec.  239. 

JOHN  LAIRD. 

Le  Regne  de  la  Pense'e.     By  PAUL  DECOSTEB,  Professeur  a  I'Universite  de 
Bruxelles.     BruxeUes :  M.  Lamertin,  1922.     Pp.  93. 

'This  is  the  sequel  to  La  Rtforme  de  la  Conscience  which  was  noticed  by 
the  present  writer  in  MIND,  April,  1920.  These  two  little  books,  each  of 
about  ninety  pages,  are  full  of  profound  thought,  and  though  not  easy 
reading  will  well  repay  study  ;  for  they  represent  an  attempt  to  develop 
a  philosophy  which  shall  hold  consistently  to  the  central  thought  of  l '  in- 
trinsic value  ".  Such  a  philosophy  owes  its  importance  to  the  fact  that  it 
is  the  spiritual  analogue  of  a  pure  mechanical  philosophy  :  both  represent 
.an  attempt  at  perfect  consistency  of  outlook.  The  one  philosophy 
stresses  reality  per  se,  and  denies  value  ;  the  other  stresses  value,  and 
denies  reality  per  se. .  The  importance  of  each  depends  on  the  extent  to 
which  it  succeeds  in  eliminating  the  fundamental  concept  of  the  other. 
For  philosophies  of  this  type,  when  given  clear  expression,  are  "  limiting 
cases  "  which  throw  the  maximum  light  on  the  conceptions  which  are  at 
man's  disposal  for  the  solution  of  his  problems,  and  enable  him  step  by 
step  to  mark  out  the  complexity  of  the  field  of  his  labours. 

The  fundamental  aim  for  philosophy,  on  M.  Decoster's  view,  is  the 
discovery  of  what  has  intrinsic  value.  In  the  second  place,  in  our  search 
>for  intrinsic  value  we  must  not  appeal  to  any  u faculty,"  such  as  knowing 
or  feeling,  etc.,  but  must  rest  on  the  whole  nature  of  man.  Thirdly,  for 
M.  Decoster,  the  possession  of  intrinsic  value  is  the  sole  test  of  reality. 

From  these  three  propositions  the  rest  of  his  argument  in  its  main  lines 
seems  to  follow  inevitably.  For  a  judgment  predicating  value  of  an  in- 
dependent real  is  a  contradiction  in  terms.  Value  supposes  that  the  sub- 
ject of  the  value  and  the  recogniser  of  it  are  the  same.  Indeed  "  recogni- 
tion!" only  covers  the  same  problem.  Strictly  speaking,  you  do  not  so 
much  recognise  value  as  act  or  create  it ;  or  rather,  genuine  recognition  is 
possible  only  as  an  element  in  the  act  of  creation. 

It  is  not  enough,  however,  to  deny  the  existence,  or  the  reality,  of  a 
'world  independent  of  a  self.  It  is  necessary  to  turn  away  at  the  outset 
even  from  an  objectivity  considered  as  essentially  related  to  a  conscious- 
ness. If  what  has  intrinsic  value  is  alone  real,  then  our  first  and  last 
concern  should  be  with  the  realisation  of  intrinsic  value.  M.  Decoster's 
fundamental  point  is  the  necessity  of  delivering  thought  "  a  la  fois  du 
souci  de  1'objectivite  et  de  la  hantise  de  1'Etre.  La  denomination  intrin- 
-seque  est  anterieure  en  droit  a  toute  determination  objective.  Qui  pour- 
suit  1'une,  doit  faire  table  rase  de  1'autre.  .  .  .  Non  moins  que  1'appar- 


NEW  BOOKS.  367 

«nce,  la  realite  est  illusoire  "  (32).  This,  which  he  endeavoured  to  justify 
in  the  Reforme  by  a  criticism  of  other  philosophies,  is  taken  in  Le  Regne,  de 
la  Pen*ee  as  the  starting  point,  as  a  direct  consequence  of  the  assertion  of 
the  supremacy  of  intrinsic  value. 

We  are  then  thrown  back  upon  the  self  as  the  ultimate  source  of  all 
value  and  all  reality  ;  the  phenomenal  world  which  is  presented  as  inde- 
pendent of  me  must  be  shown  to  be  derived  in  some  way  from  me.  Again, 
if  we  are  to  find  in  the  universe  any  more  than  a  single  self,  we  must 
obtain  our  justification  for  it  in  what  we  discover  in  the  single  self.  This 
is  one  of  M.  Decoster's  central  points  ;  and  it  is  worked  out  in  his  account 
of  man  in  society  in  Ch.  iii.  Contact  with  other  persons,  it  is  obvious,  is 
a  matter  of  varying  quality  and  degree  ;  in  its  highest  and  most  essential 
form  it  is  extremely  rare  and  not  necessarily  of  long  duration  ;  but  the 
lower  forms  have  to  be  considered  as  degradations  of  the  highest  form. 
When  we  consider  it  at  its  best,  we  find,  on  M.  Decoster's  view,  that  the 
individual  only  obtains  it  by  creating  the  other  persons  as  part  of  his  own 
personality.  The  social  bond  is  not  something  which  exists  in  its  own 
right,  but  which  must  be  continually  produced  and  maintained  by  man's 
own  effort. 

How  far  it  is  possible  resolutely  to  hold  to  the  self  as  an  "  individual 
conscious  subject "  (44)  and  yet  avoid  solipsism  ;  how  far  distinct  person- 
alities can  exist  without  being  either  separated  by  an  independent  material 
or  blended  in  a  super-personal  unity  :  are  in  a  sense  M.  Decoster's  main 
problems.  They  cannot  be  solved,  he  insists,  by  any  theoretical  phil- 
osophy :  but  philosophy  is  for  him  fundamentally  not  theoretical,  but 
practical. 

We  have  no  space  to  enter  into  a  discussion  of  the  detailed  develop- 
ment of  the  situation  whose  broad  outlines  we  have  endeavoured  to  indi- 
cate ;  M.  Decoster's  handling  is  always  vigorous  and  full  of  suggestiveness. 

LEONARD  RUSSELL. 


Lineamenti  di  Filosofia  Scettica.     By  GUISEPPE  RENSI.     2nd  edition  re- 
vised and  enlarged.     Bologna  :  Zanichelli,  1921.     Pp.  442. 

Prof.  Rensi  of  Genoa  first  published  this  work  in  1919,  and  that  a  new 
and  greatly  enlarged  edition  should  have  been  called  for  so  soon  is  the 
most  convincing  testimony  to  its  merits.  These  would  appear  to  consist 
rather  in  the  eloquence  and  literary  skill  with  which  the  case  is  argued, 
the  abundance  of  philosophic  learning  and  the  wide  range  of  illustration, 
than  in  any  special  subtlety  or  novelty  in  the  plea  for  scepticism  itself. 
In  other  words  Prof.  Rensi's  argument  is  historical  rather  than  dialectical. 
He  divides  his  book  into  three  main  sections,  the  first  of  which  uses  the  War 
as  a  peg  for  expounding  the  irrationality  of  human  activities,  while  the 
second,  called  il  diritto,  displays  the  irreconcilable  conflicts  in  social  and 
political  life.  The  third  is  called  '  philosophy, '  and  argues  for  scepticism 
from  the  existence  of  error,  evil  and  the  ineradicable  variety  of  speculative 
opinion.  In  this  last  section,  and  indeed  throughout,  absolute  idealism  is 
treated  as  the  enemy  to  be  trounced  and  exposed,  particularly  in  the 
forms  given  to  it  by  Croce  and  Gentile,  while  positivism,  relativism, 
pragmatism  and  fictionism  (Vaihinger  and  Nietzsche)  are  regarded  as 
subsidiary  species  of  scepticism  itself.  This  line  of  argument,  though  it 
derives  a  special  piquancy  from  Prof.  Rensi's  philosophic  past,  appears 
to  do  much  less  than  justice  to  the  sceptical  affinities  of  absolute  idealism, 
which  after  all  is  quite  as  much  a  denial  of  human  knowledge  as  it  is  an 
affirmation  of  absolute.  Prof.  Rensi  recognises  this  in  the  case  of 


368  NEW  BOOKS. 

Bradley,  whom  he  regards  (p.  333)  as  (mainly)  a  sceptic  furbishing  up 
again  "the  essential  theses  of  Sextus  Empiricus  "  ;  but  he  usually  seeks 
his  philosophic  allies  in  other  camps. 

That  he  can  find  such  allies  at  all  becomes  intelligible  when  we  discover 
what  he  means  by  scepticism.  It  appears  from  his  answer  to  the  old  ob- 
jection that  a  complete  denial  of  knowledge  destroys  itself  by  applying 
also  to  the  denial  itself  (p.  350  f.).  Prof.  Rensi  waves  it  aside  as  '  mere 
verbalism,'  because  for  him  scepticism  means  only  a  denial  that  philosophy 
is  knowledge,  and  leaves  both  *  facts  '  and  '  faith  '  intact.  It  can  re- 
cognise that  '  facts  '  are,  and  denies  only  that  they  can  be  explained. 
Thus  in  short,  and  in  principle,  it  is  "nothing  but  empiricism"  (p. 
358  n.).  It  is  compatible  also  with  practical  certainty  (p.  398),  and  has 
nothing  to  fear  from  a  line  of  thought  which  substitutes  it  for  theoretic. 
Consequently  it  can  swallow  pragmatism  whole,  without  a  twinge. 

But  can  it  also  digest  it  ?  The  purely  theoretic  character  Prof.  Rensi 
ascribes  to  scepticism  renders  this  doubtful.  No  doubt,  if  to  overcome 
scepticism  it  is  necessary  to  do  so  'theoretically,'  "on  the  ground  on 
which  it  arises  and  with  arms  taken  solely  from  that  ground"  (p.  398), 
and  if  there  is  no  conceivable  objection  to  the  position  that  a  belief  may 
be  at  once  theoretically  false  and  practically  indispensable  and  all  the 
better  for  being  false,  pragmatism  not  only  cannot  overcome  scepticism, 
but  must  merge  into  it.  For  pragmatism  does  not  offer  any  '  purely 
theoretic  '  cure  for  doubt.  It  must  admit  that  "  reason  as  such"  does  not 
extricate  itself  from  the  contradictions  in  which  it  gets  involved.  But 
then  pragmatism  does  not  draw  the  old  sceptical  inference  from  this 
situation,  but  deals  with  it  in  an  essentially  novel  manner.  It  points  out 
that  there  is  no  such  thing  as  *  reason  as  such,'  that  it  is  an  abstraction  or 
fiction.  It  refuses  to  sever  'theoretic  '  truth  from  its  '  practical '  conse- 
quences. It  regards  the  union  of  theoretic  falsity  with  practical  value  as 
a  monstrosity,  which  can  hardly  be  tolerated  as  a  starting-point,  and  can- 
not stand  as  the  conclusion,  of  a  philosophic  inquiry.  In  short  it  challenges 
the  finality  of  the  distinction  between  theory  and  practice,  and  the  irrele- 
vance of  practical  value  to  theoretic  truth.  And  so  it  is  entitled  to  hold 
that  the  unworkableness  of  a  belief  is  an  argument  against  it.  If  a  pro- 
fessed '  sceptic '  acts  as  if  he  believed,  he  casts  a  doubt  on  his  profession. 
His  disbelief  falls  under  suspicion  of  being  make-believe.  And  if  he  can- 
not but  affirm  by  his  acts  the  belief  he  repudiates  in  words,  he  refutes  his 
scepticism  in  a  far  more  final  and  conclusive  manner  than  by  any  trick 
of  dialectics.  This  is  not  to  say,  however,  that  all  scepticism  is  impos- 
sible. It  implies  only  that,  to  be  tenable,  scepticism  must  become 
practical  and  develop  also  a  mode  of  living, 

F.  0.  S.  SCHILLER. 

The  Psychology  of  Society.  By  MORRIS  GINSBERG,  M.A.,  Lecturer  in 
Philosophy,  University  College,  London.  London  :  Methuen  &  Co., 
Ltd.,  1921.  Pp.  xvi,  174.  5s. 

This  book  is  presumably  intended  as  a  general  introduction  and  guide  for 
those  who  want  to  know  what  Social  Psychology  is  about,  the  sort  of 
things  that  are  being  discussed  and  the  different  views  that  are  being 
maintained  within  that  branch  of  knowledge.  As  such,  it  fulfils  its  pur- 
pose admirably.  Mr.  Ginsberg's  style  is  always  perfectly  lucid,  his  com- 
ments and  criticisms  are  always  shrewd  and  to  the  point,  he  has  a  wide 
knowledge  of  recent  literature  on  the  subject,  and  he  has  something  to  tell 
us  about  most  of  the  important  questions  that  have  been  raised  and  the 
views  that  have  been  put  forward.  There  are  discussions  on  the  nature 


NEW  BOOKS.  369 

and  functions  of  Instinct,  on  the  place  of  Reason  and  Will  in  social  life, 
on  the  idea  of  a  group-mind,  on  the  General  Will,  on  the  nature  of  com- 
munity, on  the  psychology  of  the  crowd,  on  organisation  and  democracy, 
and  several  other  kindred  questions. 

The  greater  part  of  the  book  is  critical.  Mr.  Ginsberg  is  a  very  cautious 
and  conservative  thinker  and  very  slow  to  commit  himself  to  any  positive 
conclusion.  When  he  does,  it  is  generally  to  some  well-tested  view  which 
can  claim  weighty  support.  Thus  he  definitely  ranges  himself  on  the  side 
of  those  who,  like  Prof.  Hobhouse,  look  to  the  individual  personality 
rather  than  to  the  organised  society  as  the  fundamental  fact  in  moral  and 
social  questions.  He  definitely  rejects  any  idea  of  a  group-mind, — his 
criticisms  of  the  obscurities  and  confusions  of  Dr.  McDougall's  position 
on  this  question  are  particularly  good, — and  he  refuses  to  accept  any  such 
notion  of  a  General  Will  as  that  put  forward  by  Dr.  Bosanquet  and  other 
Idealists.  He  is  also  in  reaction  against  the  modern  anti-intellectualist 
tendencies  in  Psychology,  and  brings  against  them  the  well-founded  re- 
proach that  they  are  founded  on  an  entirely  inadequate  idea  of  what 
reason  and  the  intellect  are  and  on  * '  a  false  separation  between  reason  or 
rational  will  and  impulse ".  His  summary  of  the  objections  to  Dr. 
McDougall's  view  of  the  role  of  the  instincts  is  clear  and  forcible.  So, 
too,  is  his  criticism  of  Mr.  Trotter  and  his  idea  of  the  herd-instinct.  He 
points  out  very  clearly  the  dangerous  tendency  of  both  these  writers  to 
over-simplification  in  their  attempts  to  reduce  a  number  of  complex  facts 
to  some  one  simple  process,  attempts  which  invariably  end  in  leaving  out 
just  those  features  in  the  situation  that  we  most  want  to  explain.  He 
complains,  equally  justifiably,  of  the  tendency  of  such  writers  to  regard 
the  instincts  as  a  number  of  independent  entities,  and  "  to  look  at  the 
organism  as  a  whole  as  a  kind  of  aggregate  of  them  ".  In  fact,  on  almost 
every  subject  that  he  touches,  he  has  something  shrewd  and  pertinent 
to  say. 

Yet  even  in  his  criticisms  he  leaves  us  too  often  with  a  sense  of  incom- 
pleteness. We  feel  that  there  is  a  lot  more  to  be  said,  and  that  he  often 
leaves  off  just  as  he  was  getting  to  the  real  fundamental  point.  We  get 
the  impression  rather  of  a  series  of  occasional  reflexions  than  of  a  systematic 
treatment  of  the  subject.  No  doubt  this  arises  in  part  from  the  task  that 
he  has  set  himself  of  dealing  with  so  many  different  points  in  such  a  brief 
space.  But  it  is  particularly  unfortunate  when  he  comes  to  deal  with  Dr. 
Bosanquet's  view  of  the  General  Will.  His  criticisms  here  are  fair  as  far 
as  they  go.  But  Dr.  Bosanquet  would  probably  answer  that  they  had 
never  faced  the  real  fundamental  points  at  issue.  A  view  which  rests  so 
much  on  such  a  deeply-laid  metaphysical  foundation  cannot  be  thus  lightly 
disposed  of  in  a  few  pages. 

The  general  criticisms  that  might  be  made  on  the  book  are,  firstly,  that 
it  shows  a  certain  lack  of  originality,  secondly,  that  it  is  somewhat  discon- 
nected, and,  finally,  that  it  gives  us  very  little  but  negative  results.  These 
are  really,  perhaps,  criticisms  rather  of  the  present  state  of  our  knowledge 
in  these  matters  than  of  the  author  individually.  It  is  true  that  hardly 
any  positive  results  have  yet  been  attained  in  Social  Psychology,  except 
those  which  are  plainly  false  or  inadequate.  It  is  true,  also,  that  no  one 
has  yet  found  a  single  guiding  thread  through  the  complicated  maze  of 
social  phenomena.  But  it  is  a  question  whether  there  is  not  a  certain 
obligation  on  anyone  who  writes  a  book  on  the  subject  to  make  some  at- 
tempt to  advance  the  study  to  some  degree  and  to  give  us  some  new  know- 
ledge. Mr.  Ginsberg's  book  gives  a  great  deal  of  information  to  those  who 
wish  to  know  how  far  we  have  got.  But  it  is  not  likely  to  take  us  any 
further. 

G.  C.  FIELD. 
24 


370  NEW  BOOKS. 

The  Psycho- Analytical  Study  of  the  Family.  By  J.  C.  FLUGEL,  B.A. 
The  International  Psycho-Analytical  Press.  Pp.  x  +  259.  Price 
10s.  6d.  net. 

Mr.  Fliigel  has  written  a  book  which  not  only  well  sustains  the  standard 
set  by  the  earlier  volumes  of  this  series  but  also  fills  a  distinct  gap  in 
psychological  literature. 

Many  writers  of  the  psycho-analytic  school  have  dealt  with  different 
aspects  of  the  relations  between  parents  and  children  and  some  of  these 
are,  of  course,  at  the  very  root  of  psycho-analytic  doctrine.  But  so  far 
as  the  present  reviewer  is  aware  this  is  the  first  serious  attempt  to  deal 
comprehensively  with  the  whole  subject.  It  is  written  primarily  for 
professional  psychologists  and  advanced  students  to  whom  it  will  un- 
questionably prove  of  great  value. 

But  in  view  of  the  very  great  importance  of  the  subject  and  the  rarity 
of  good  books  dealing  with  it  one  rather  wishes  that  Mr.  Fltigel  had  been 
able  to  see  his  way  to  tempering  the  wind  for  the  benefit  of  the  general 
reader.  Ordinary  people,  unversed  in  psychology,  would  gieatly  benefit 
from  a  knowledge  of  the  psychological  forces  at  work  within  the  family. 
They  will  scarcely  be  able  to  profit  from  Mr.  Fliigel's  book,  however,  for 
it  presupposes  a  knowledge  of  psycho-analytic  doctrine  and  a  familiarity 
with  psycho-analytic  concepts  which  few  people  possess.  To  describe 
the  natural  revolt  of  the  child  against  parental  authority  as  '  hatred ' 
and  the  early  deviations  of  potential  sex  impulses  upon  the  nearest  ob- 
jects as  '  incest  tendencies  ',  is  psychologically  unimpeachable  but  is  cer- 
tain to  arouse  the  opposition  of  the  laity.  But  it  is  notoriously  difficult 
to  write  a  book  which  is  both  technically  accurate  and  easily  assimilated 
by  the  public  and  this  criticism  is  only  prompted  by  regret  that  so  valu- 
able a  work  should  be  limited  to  a  specialised  public. 

Perhaps  the  special  merit  of  the  work  is  the  way  in  which  the  author 
shows  how  the  psychological  factors  which  operate  in  early  childhood 
exert  a  profound  influence  on  the  child's  subsequent  development  in  every 
direction.  This  is  seldom  properly  realised  and,  even  where  it  is,  parents 
do  not  possess  the  technical  knowledge  which  would  enable  them  to 
understand  the  'sense'  in  which  various  circumstances  produce  their 
effect.  Family  life  constitutes  a  replica  in  miniature  of  the  social 
environment  into  which  the  child  must  ultimately  enter  after  adolescence. 
Love  and  jealousy,  dependence  and  emulation,  authority,  self-assertion, 
and  pride  are  all  represented  on  a  scale  which  though  small  to  the 
adult  is  full-sized  to  the  child.  And  it  is  on  the  reactions  which  be- 
came habitual  in  the  early  years  of  family  life  that  the  type  of  behaviour 
in  similar  situations  will  afterwards  depend. 

Mr.  Fliigel's  application  of  early  influences  to  the  religious  and  social 
reactions  of  the  adult  is  of  particular  interest  and  seems  to  show  how 
easily  the  whole  of  our  national  outlook  on  these  questions  could  be  trans- 
formed by  a  single  generation  of  intelligent  upbringing.  This  same  pro- 
cess would  probably  remove  one  of  the  chief  predisposing  causes  of 
neuroses.  But  the  millennium  will  scarcely  come  yet;  even  the  most 
enlightened  and  sagacious  parent  would  find  it  difficult  to  steer  an  even 
course  among  the  manifold  dangers  which  Mr.  Fliigel  unfolds,  and  much 
remains  to  be  done  before  the  best-intentioned  persons  can  be  sure  of  not 
Handicapping  their  children  by  unwitting  indiscretions  of  one  kind  or 
another.  Probably  it  will  never  prove  either  possible  or  desirable  to 
reduce  the  treatment  of  children  to  an  exact  science  :  it  is  more  likely 
that  the  desired  improvement  will  be  brought  about  by  a  gradual  eradi- 
cation of  complexes  from  the  minds  of  successive  generations,  so  that  each 


NEW  BOOKS.  371 

deals  with  the  next  more  naturally  and  less  at  the  dictation  of  parentally 
inspired  prejudices. 

But  whether  this  be  so  or  not  there  can  be  no  doubt  that  Mr.  Fliigel's 
book  will  be  counted  as  a  foundation  stone  of  the  steadily  consolidating 
science  of  those  family  relationships  which  are  at  the  root  of  social  life. 

W.  WHATELY  SMITH. 


The  Esthetic  Attitude.     By  HERBERT  S.  LANGFELD.     New  York  :  Har- 
court,  Brace  &  Howe,  1920.     Pp.  287. 

This  work  is  mainly  a  psychological  discussion  as  to  what  constitutes  tho 
essential  nature  of  the  aesthetic  attitude.  The  objective  aspect  of  the 
problem,  however,  is  constantly  dealt  with  in  the  numerous  references  to 
objects  of  art,  especially  pictures,  of  which  there  are  seventy  prints,  well 
chosen,  and  most  of  them  excellent  reproductions. 

The  main  differentiating  characteristic  of  this  work  is  that  it  explicitly 
aims  at  the  development  of  aesthetic  appreciation  in  the  reader.  Yet 
this  is  sought  not  by  means  of  suggestion  and  the  expression  of  admira- 
tion, which  is  one  means  of  aesthetic  education,  but  by  an  attempt  to 
make  clear  how  the  aesthetic  attitude  is  produced,  and  what  are  the  marks 
of  a  pseudo-aesthetic  attitude. 

Whatever  views  one  may  hold  as  to  the  effect,  on  the  enjoyment  of 
beauty,  of  psychologising  upon  one's  attitude  towards  it,  one  may  wel- 
come an  attempt  along  the  lines  indicated.  For  it  is  a  problem  on  which 
we  need  the  fullest  information  and  discussion.  Some  hold  that  in  turn- 
ing attention  inward  on  the  mental  process  involved  in  the  enjoyment  of 
beauty,  we  are  destroying  our  capacity  for  that  enjoyment.  Certainly  at 
the  moment  of  psychol  >gising  we  are  not  admiring  and  enjoying  the 
beautiful  to  the  full.  But  we  must  consider  the  question  in  its  widest 
aspect.  Does  an  interest  in  psychological  aesthetic  problems  on  the  whole 
lessen  our  enjoyment  of  beauty  ?  We  know  that  the  literary  scholar  be- 
comes engrossed  in  matters  of  historical  and  biographical  facts  which 
divert  his  attention  for  the  moment  from  the  purely  aesthetic  appreciation 
of  a  poet's  creative  work,  but  we  also  know  that,  taken  as  a  whole,  the 
literary  scholar  enjoys  a  much  wider  aesthetic  appreciation  than  the  un- 
taught ;  and  indeed  the  interest  in  facts  of  literary  history  in  their  re- 
lations to,  say,  the  poem  in  question,  sometimes  approximates  to  an 
element  in  a  unified  aesthetic  attitude  towards  the  poem. 

In  a  similar  way  can  we  not  say  that  Wordsworth's  interest  in  the  sub- 
jective aspect  of  his  appreciation  of  the  beautiful  in  nature  is  sometimes 
so  closely  connected  with  that  appreciation  of  nature  as  to  enrich  it  rather 
than  to  detract  from  it  ? 

In  both  the  cases,  of  course,  the  value  (other  than  its  aesthetic  value) 
of  the  intellectual  interest  may  well  justify  its  cultivation,  though  to  rely 
on  this  alone  would  be  quite  different  from  claiming  that  by  psychologis- 
ing we  can  enhance  aesthetic  enjoyment.  But  even  admitting  that  mo- 
mentarily any  such  psychologising  is  inconsistent  with  the  purely 
aesthetic  attitude  or  the  attitude  of  literary  criticism,  the  right  line  of 
argument  seems  to  be  that  in  the  long  run  such  an  added  interest  will 
result  in  a  wider  cultivation  of  aesthetic  enjoyment  and  the  adding  to  the 
variety  and  so  the  permanence  and  predominance  of  aesthetic  interests, 
apart  from  the  possibility  of  its  influence  in  the  selection  of  objects  for 
aesthetic  appreciation  and  on  the  development  of  art. 

It  might  have  led  to  a  more  original  contribution  to  aesthetics  if  Dr. 
Langfeld  had  developed  this  aspect  of  the  subject  more  fully  throughout 


372  NEW  BOOKS. 

his  book.  He  is  largely  content,  however,  to  give  a  general  survey  of 
some  leading  psychological  doctrines  as  to  aesthetic  appreciation  and  to 
discuss  such  characteristics  or  supposed  characteristics  of  the  aesthetic 
attitude  as  the  following  :  detachment  and  isolation,  the  absence  of  utility 
and  purpose,  stimulation  combined  with  repose,  the  feeling  of  unreality, 
psychological  distance. 

Still  more  fully  is  discussed  the  doctrine  of  empathy.  And  here,  while 
Dr.  Langfeld  explictly  guards  against  the  assertion  that  actual  sensations 
must  be  experienced  in  the  empathic  interpretation  of  laws,  of  move- 
ments in  a  picture,  etc. ,  his  expositions  here  and  elsewhere  seem  to  stress 
unduly  the  influence  of  movement  in  mental  process  and  to  approach 
something  like  a  behaviourist  view  that  mind  can  be  interpreted  in  terms 
of  motor  reaction.  This  tendency  appears  even  in  the  discussion  of  ' '  At- 
tention as  a  Unifying  Process,"  when,  for  example,  he  writes:  "The 
attention  to  different  musical  compositions  involves  very  different  co- 
ordinations of  emphatic  responses  ;  but  since,  normally,  the  very  same 
muscle  groups  are  employed,  it  is  impossible  to  listen  to  two  pieces  of 
music  simultaneously  ". 

A  good  deal  of  recent  experimental  material  very  relevant  to  some  of 
the  problems  discussed  is  ignored  by  Dr.  Langfeld.  The  book,  however, 
is  written  in  a  very  clear  style  ;  fallacies  are  not  at  any  time  concealed  by 
obscure  expression  as  is  sometimes  the  case.  The  work  will  serve  as  a 
useful  introduction  more  especially  to  the  study  of  the  point  of  contact 
between  psychological  and  pictorial  art.  Perhaps  the  most  useful  part  of 
the  book  is  the  discussion  on  Unity  (under  Unity  and  Imagination  and 
Illustration  of  Unity  from  the  Fine  Arts)  in  which  Dr.  Langfeld  allows 
due  recognition  to  the  significance  of  the  nature  of  attention  in  aesthetic 
appreciation. 

C.  W.  VALENTINE. 

The  Elements  of  Social  Justice.    By  L.  T.  HOBHOUSE.     London  :  George 
Allen  &  Unwin,  Ltd.,  1922.     Pp.  206. 

Thirty  years  ago  it  looked  as  though  '  Natural  Rights '  were  coming  to 
be  regarded  as  having  outlived  their  usefulness  and  were  to  sink  into 
obscurity.  Criticism  was  directed  against  them  by  writers  as  different 
as  Huxley  and  Ritchie  ;  and,  though  the  critics  may  not  have  agreed 
with  each  other,  they  were  at  one  in  pointing  out  that  some  of  these 
Rights  were  inconsistent,  when  pressed,  with  others,  and  that  there 
were  dangers  in  using  so  uncertain  a  guide  as  the  conception  of  Rights 
appeared  to  be.  The  defenders  of  Natural  Rights  were  reduced  to  arguing 
that  the  formula  ought  to  be  retained  in  default  of  something  better.  It 
is  true  that  philosophers  never  gave  up  using  the  expression  :  but,  as 
Prof.  Hobhouse  points  out  in  this  volume,  they  would  have  been  more 
consistent  if  they  had  done  so.  Natural  rights  seemed  to  be  employed  by 
them  either  as  a  somewhat  ambiguous  substitute  for  political  ideals,  or  as 
guiding  conceptions  which  came  in  whenever  the  ideas  of  social  good  or 
human  progress  were  too  wide  to  give  any  help.  Partly  the  term  was 
retained  as  a  concession  to  ordinary  language.  Aristotelians  like  Green 
and  Ritchie  would  have  felt  uncomfortable  if  they  had  seemed  to  suggest 
that  expressions  which  had  inspired  enthusiasm  and  had  promoted 
progress  could  be  laid  on  one  side  as  though  they  had  entirely  lost 
their  meaning.  And  it  is  impossible  not  to  feel  grateful  to  a  writer  like 
Prof.  Hobhouse,  whether  he  call  himself  an  Aristotelian  or  not,  who  is 
willing  to  assume  that  such  words  as  rights,  liberty,  or  equality  must  be 
prepared  to  yield  a  useful  meaning  if  they  are  carefully  analysed,  and  to 


NEW   BOOKS.  373 

take  the  trouble  to  examine  them  seriously  in  order  to  separate  the  valu- 
able elements  which,  on  the  lowest  estimate,  they  must  contain.  In  part 
this  book  is  to  be  regarded  as  applying  principles  which  the  author  has 
already  explained  in  The  Rational  Good.  The  several  essays  contained  in 
it  can  no  doubt  be  understood  by  themselves,  as  each  of  them  endeavours 
to  sift  the  meaning  of  some  one  conception  which  is  in  current  use.  But 
these  examinations  are  conducted  on  a  common  principle.  The  advertise- 
ment to  the  present  volume  describes  its  object }  rather  strangely,  as  being 
"to  show  that  social  and  political  institutions  are  not  ends  in  them- 
selves ".  It  is  true  that  the  first  sentence  of  the  book  asserts  this.  But 
Prof.  Hobhouse  does  not  appear  to  prove  this  here  :  nor  is  he  obliged  to 
do  so,  for  he  has  advanced  arguments  in  support  of  that  thesis  before. 
But  it  does  no  doubt  amount  to  an  additional  proof  if  it  is  shown  that  his 
theory  of  social  good  enables  him  to  give  an  intelligible  meaning  to  the 
conceptions  which  he  discusses  and  to  extract  full  value  from  them. 
It  would  be  out  of  place  to  examine  here  the  principles  which  are  ex- 
plained in  The  Rational  Good.  Those  who  do  not  know  that  work  are 
provided  by  the  author  with  a  convenient  summary  in  the  first  chapter 
of  this  volume.  There  follow  discussions  of  rights  and  duties,  liberty, 
justice  and  equality,  the  payment  of  service,  property  and  economic 
organisation,  social  and  personal  factors  in  wealth,  industrial  organisation, 
and  democracy.  All  of  these  are  so  carefully  and  patiently  conducted, 
with  so  full  a  regard  for  all  considerations  which  might  be  advanced,  that 
it  would  require  an  amount  of  space  equal  to  that  occupied  by  the  discus- 
sions themselves  to  make  any  adequate  remarks  on  them.  In  two  respects 
only  does  Prof.  Hobhouse  seem  at  times  to  lose  his  judicial  attitude.  He 
is  apt  to  be  impatient  of  the  idealist  philosophers,  and  he  occasionally 
shows  affinity  for  that  belief  in  the  wrongness  of  his  country's  actions 
which,  while  it  may  place  the  Englishman  who  adopts  it  on  a  moral  and 
political  level  far  above  that  occupied  by  his  fellow-countryman  who  be- 
lieves that  his  country  is  always  right,  is  ultimately  not  much  more 
worthy  of  a  philosopher.  Those  who  are  able  to  accept  Prof.  Hobhouse's 
social  principles  will  find  their  attitude  strengthened  in  this  volume :  and 
those  who  have  doubts  will  at  least  feel  that  he  can  give  an  account  of  the 
ideas  which  he  discusses  such  as  can  win  their  sympathy,  and  that  he 
does  not  avoid  difficulties  by  a  phrase  or  an  evasion. 

P.  V.  M.  BBNECKB. 

Bemerkungen  ftber  den  Platonischen  Dialog  Parmenides.  By  HABALD 
HOFFDING.  (Bibliothek  der  Philosophie :  21  Band.)  Berlin:  L. 
Simion,  1921.  Pp.  56. 

A  pamphlet  by  so  distinguished  an  author  as  the  veteran  HofFding  is  al- 
ways a  welcome  addition  to  philosophical  literature.  But  I  cannot  see 
that  the  present  brochure  really  throws  any  new  light  on  its  subject.  The 
view  is  expressed  that  the  structure  of  the  Parmenides  is  so  inartistic  and 
the  sophistry  of  some  of  the  reasoning  so  gross  that  it  is  fair  to  conjecture 
that  we  are  dealing  with  papers  never  intended  for  circulation  but  given 
to  the  world  posthumously  by  the  unwise  admiration  of  disciples.  I  am 
afraid  that  this  judgment  means  that  Hoffding,  like  many  writers  on  Plato, 
inhibits  his  sense  of  humour  when  he  opens  that  philosopher's  works. 
Failure  to  recognise  the  presence  of  a  peculiar  mischievous  humour  has 
hindered  the  understanding  of  a  great  deal  of  Plato  ;  it  makes  the  Par- 
menides wholly  unintelligible.  Yet  there  is  really  no  great  mystery  about 
the  dialogue,  and  Plato  himself  has  given  us  the  key  to  it  by  the  plain 
intimation  that  it  is  to  be  taken  as  an  imitation  of  the  method  of  Zeno 


374  NEW  BOOKS. 

with  the  opponents  of  Parmenides,  a  method  which  he  is  careful  to  de- 
scribe for  us.  Plato  takes  a  number  of  objections  to  the  doctrine  of  the 
"  participation  "  of  sensible  things  in  iidrj  and  states  them  with  great  force. 
The  objections  are  not  his  own,  and  there  is  not  the  slightest  reason  to 
assume,  as  Hoffding  does,  that  he  thought  them  really  dangerous.  In 
point  of  fact,  they  are  all  fallacious,  but  it  is  not  Plato's  game  to  tell  us 
so.  He  leaves  them  where  they  are  and  turns  on  the  disciples  of  the 
Eleatics  from  whom  the  objections  come.  "Socrates'  theory  leads  to 
difficulties  ? "  he  says.  "  Well,  take  your  own  doctrine  of  the  One,  let  it 
be  subjected  to  a  dialectic  like  your  own,  and  see  how  you  like  its  con- 
sequences." When  one  has  once  grasped  the  point  that  the  whole  thing 
is  a  subtle  jest,  a  turning  of  the  Megarian  dialectic  on  the  men  of  Megara, 
one  is  in  a  position  to  appreciate  the  structure  of  the  dialogue  for  the 
masterpiece  of  art  it  really  ie.  Hoffding  misses  the  fun,  asks  no  questions 
about  the  address  of  the  satire  and  so  falls  into  the  mistake  of  assuming 
both  that  Plato  was  perplexed  by  the  paralogisms  of  the  first  part  and  was 
unaware  that  there  is  a  great  deal  of  "  sophistry  "  in  the  second.  He  even 
makes  the  singular  mistake  of  saying  that  the  antithesis  One — Many  is 
badly  chosen  for  Plato's  purposes  and  that  he  would  have  done  better  to 
deal  with  that  of  Same — Other,  making  here  a  curious  error  of  fact.  He 
quotes  Farm.  139d  for  the  view  that  the  (frvats  of  the  One  is  identical  with 
that  of  the  Same.  But  he  has  omitted  an  oi>x-  Plato  expressly  says 
that  the  two  things  are  not  the  same  and  gives  an  unanswerable  reason  for 
the  distinction,  viz.,  that  what  is  the  "  same  as  2  "  is  not  1  but  2. 

A.  E.  TAYLOR. 

Die  Differentizlle  Psychologic  in  ihren  methodischen  Grundlagen.  Von 
WILLIAM  STERN.  Dritte  Auflage.  Leipzig  :  J.  A.  Barth,  1921. 
S.  x  +  546.  M.  63 ;  geb.  M.  72. 

This  well-known  work  was  first  published  in  1911.  It  was  a  comprehen- 
sive review  of  the  researches  which  had  been  carried  out  upon  the  nature, 
variety,  and  significance  of  individual  differences,  and  it  contained  an 
original  contribution  to  its  problems  which  was  of  great  importance.  For 
a  considerable  time  now  the  volume  has  been  out  of  print,  and  there  was 
every  justification  for  its  republication.  An  attempt  has  been  made  to 
bring  it  up  to  date,  by  adding  a  survey  of  the  development  of  the  psycho- 
logical study  of  individual  differences  since  1911,  and  a  bibliography  of 
recent  work. 

Both  the  survey  and  the  bibliography  might  have  been  improved.  The 
former,  interesting  as  it  is,  is  a  rather  summary  and  off-hand  piece  of 
work.  It  consists  of  three  short  sections,  the  first  dealing  with  the 
significance  of  recent  studies  of  individual  differences  from  the  point  of 
view  of  general  theoretical  psychology,  the  second  discussing  some  of  the 
practical  applications  of  psychological  tests,  and  the  third  giving  an  ac- 
count of  developments  in  the  methodology  of  the  subject.  In  each  section 
references  are  made  to  the  most  outstanding  pieces  of  research  in  the  field 
surveyed.  A  mere  reference  to  large  numbers  of  books  and  papers  is  not, 
however,  of  great  value.  A  more  reasoned  discussion,  and  a  real  attempt 
at  an  appraisement  of  the  works  referred  to  should  have  been  attempted. 

The  bibliography  is  fairly  comprehensive,  for  it  contains  the  titles  of 
over  430  books  and  papers  which  have  been  published  since  1911.  Even 
so  it  is  by  no  means  complete.  To  take  a  single  illustration,  the  section 
on  statistics  contains  no  reference  to  the  important  work  of  Prof.  G.  H. 
Thompson.  And  a  glance  at  many  other  sections  shows  similar  omissions 


NEW  BOOKS.  375 

in  regard  to  other  branches  of  research.  The  point  is,  not  that  such  a  list 
should  be  complete,  for  that  is  practically  impossible  in  a  subject  in  which 
publications  appear  with  such  bewildering  speed  as  is  the  case,  for  instance, 
with  the  modern  investigations  of  "mental  tests,"  but  that  the  biblio- 
graphy should  be  selective,  and  that  short  descriptive  and  critical  notes 
should  be  added. 

However  Die  Differentielle  Psychologie  remains  a  standard  work,  and 
its  reappearance  will,  no  doubt,  be  heartily  welcomed.  Though  the  addi- 
tions are  rather  scanty,  they  may  yet  help  to  set  new  investigators  at 
work  along  fruitful  lines  of  enquiry. 

F.  C.  B. 


La  Filosofia  di  Giorgio  Berkeley  (Metafisica  e  Gnoseologia).     By  ADOLFO 
LEVI.     Turin,  Bocca  Bros.,  1922.     Pp.  102. 

Mr.  Levi  has  brought  to  his  study  of  Berkeley  the  same  wealth  of  know- 
ledge of  the  literature  of  the  whole  subject  which  distinguishes  his  work 
on  Plato.  He  rightly  comments  on  the  singular  error  of  the  average 
historian  of  philosophy  who  confines  his  attention  to  Berkeley's  juvenile 
writings  and  contrives  to  fit  them  into  his  preconceived  scheme  as  a  mere 
half-way  house  between  Locke  and  Hume.  Mr.  Levi's  own  work  aims  at 
showing  the  substantial  "  autonomy  "  of  Berkeley's  philosophical  thought 
and  tracing  the  steady  and  consistent  line  of  development  which  it  follows 
from  the  Common-Place  Book  right  on  to  Siris.  On  the  main  point  that 
Berkeley  is  not  a  "  continuator  of  Locke,"  the  best  recent  British  and 
American  critics,  would  be  pretty  much  in  accord  with  Mr.  Levi,  and  his 
conclusion  could  be  further  reinforced  by  the  considerations  recently  ad- 
duced from  America  which  go  to  show  that  Berkeley's  criticism  of  Locke 
is  mainly  motived  by  the  acceptance  of  Locke's  doctrines  by  his  own  real 
enemies,  the  "minute  philosophers,"  who  treat  the  perceived  world  as 
phenomenal  of  an  unperceived  real  world  of  Newtonian  "corpuscles" 
and  run  the  risk  of  making  this  Newtonian  "  matter"  at  least  co- 
eternal  with  God.  It  is  naturally  welcome  to  Berkeley's  countrymen 
to  receive  so  admirable  a  study  of  him  from  Italy.  If  it  is  not  presumptu- 
ous, I  should  like  to  express  the  wish  that  Mr.  Levi  would  lay  us  under 
a  further  obligation  by  producing  an  equally  independent  study  of  Locke 
himself,  one  of  the  most  generally  misunderstood  of  philosophers. 

A.  E.  T. 


Received  also  : — 

S.  Dasgupta,  A  History  of  Indian  Phiiotophy,  Vol.  J.,  Cambridge  Univer- 
sity Press,  1922,  pp.  xvi,  528. 

L.  LeVy-Bruhl,  La  Mentalite  Primitive,  Paris,  F.  Alcan,  1922,  pp.  iii, 
537. 

H.  B.  Smith,  Foundation*  of  Formal  Lojic,  Philadelphia,  University  of 
Pennsylvania  Press,  1922,  pp.  56. 

Sir  C.  Walston,  Harmonium  and  GYn.svucms  Evolution,  London,  J.  Murray, 
1922,  pp'.  xvi,  463. 

M.  Engel,  Gedauhm  uber  das  Denken  (Bibliothek  der  Philosophic,  ed.  by 
L.  Stein,  22  Band),  Berlin,  L.  Simion  Nf.,  1922,  pp.  73. 

L.  Lavelle,  La  Dialerti/ue  du  Monde  Sensible,  Strasbourg,  Palais  de 
1'Universite,  1921,  pp.  xlv,  228. 


376  NEW  BOOKS. 

L.  Lavelle,  La  Perception  Visuelle  de  la  Profondeur,  Strasbourg,  Palais  de 
I'Universite,  1921,  pp.  72. 

R.  Berthelot,  Un  Romantisme  Utilitaire,  fitude  sur  le  Mouvement  Pragma- 
tiste,  Vol.  III.,  Le  Pragmatisme  Religieux  chez  W.  James  et  chez 
les  Catholique*  Modernistes,  Paris,  F.  Alcan,  1922,  pp.  428. 

H.  Delacroix,  La  Religion  et  la  Foi,  Paris,  F.  Alcan,  1922,  pp.  xii,  462. 

B.  Croce,  Esthetic,  trans,  by  D.  Ainslie,  2nd  Edition,  London,  Macmillan 

&  Co.  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  xxx,  503. 
A.  Einstein,    Sidelights  on  Relativity,   trans,  by  G.  B.  Jeffrey  and  W. 

Perrett,  London,  Methuen  &  Co.  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  56. 
J.  Becquerel,  Le  Principe  de  Relativite  et  la  The'orie  de  la  Gravitation, 

Paris,  Gauthier-Villars  et  Cie,  1922,  pp.  ix,  342. 

F.  Michaud,  Rayonnement  et  Gravitation,  Paris,  Gauthier-Villars  et  Cie, 

1922,  pp.  61. 
L.  Bloch,  Le  Prtncipe  de  la  Relativite  et  la  The'orie  d' Einstein,  Paris, 

Gauthier-Villars  et  Cie,  1922,  pp.  42. 
General  Chapel,  E 'Mer-filectricite  Relativisme,  Paris,  Gauthier-Villars  et 

Cie,  1922,  pp.  40. 
W.  H.  V.  Reade,  A  Criticism  of  Einstein  and  his  Problem,  Oxford,  B. 

Blackwell,  1922,  pp.  126. 
R.  B.  Appleton,  The  Elements  of  Greek  Philosophy  from  Thales  to  Aristotle, 

London,  Methueu  and  Co.  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  xiv,  170. 
E.  Dupreel,  La  Legende  Soaatique  et  les  Sources  de  Platan,  Brussels,  R. 

Sand,  1922,  pp.  450. 

C.  Lalo,  Aristote  (Les  Philosophes),  Paris,  Delaplane,  pp.  160. 

E.  Guson,  La  Philosophic  au  Moyen  Age,  2  vols.,  Paris,  Payot  et  Cie, 

1922,  pp.  160,  159. 
M.  de  Wulf,  Philosophy  and  Civilization  in  the  Middle'  Ages,  Princeton 

University  Press,  1922,  pp.  x,  313. 

K.  Vorlander,  Immanuel  Kants  Leben,  Leipzig,  F.  Meiner,  pp.  xi,  223. 
M.   Heynacher,    Goethes  Philosophic  aus  seinen    Werken,    2nd   Edition, 

Leipzig,  F.  Meiner,  pp.  cxxxi,  319. 

G.  Gurwitsch,  Kant  und  Fichte  als  Rousseau-Interpreten,  Off-print  from 

"Kant-Studien,"  XXVII.,  1922,  pp.  26. 
J.  G.  Fichte,  Einige   Vorlesungen  iiber   die   Bestimmung  des  Gelehrten, 

2nd  enlarged  Edition,  Leipzig,  F.  Meiner,  1922,  pp.  61. 
G.  Gurwitsch,  Die  Einheit  der  Fichteschen  Philosophic,  Berlin,  A.  Col- 

lignon,  1922,  pp.  38. 
J.  McT.  E.  McTaggart,  Studies  in  the  Hegelian  Dialectic,  Second  Edition, 

Cambridge  University  Press,  1922,  pp.  xvi,  255. 

F.  Duine,  La  Mennais,  Paris,  Gamier  Freres,  1922,  pp.  iii,  389. 

R.  Ardigo,  Scritti  Vari,  collected  and  arranged  by  G.  Marchesini,  Florence, 

F.  Le  Monnier,  pp.  301. 
A.  A.  Brill,  Fundamental  Conceptions  of  Psycho-analysis,   London,  G. 

Allen  &  Unwin  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  vii,  344. 
W.  Brown,  Suggestion  and  Mental  Analysis,  London  University  Press 

Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  165. 
V.  M.  Firth,  The  Machinery  of  the  Mind,  London,  G.  Allen  &  Unwin  Ltd., 

1922,  pp.  95. 
L.  Vivante,  Delia  Intelligenza  nell'  Espressione,  Rome,  P.  Maglioue  &  C. 

Strini,  1922,  pp.  ix,  229. 
H.  Macnaghten,  Emile  Coue,  The  Man  and  His  Work,  London,  Methuen 

&  Co.  Ltd.,  pp.  52. 

G.  Belot,  Etudes  de  Morale  Positive,  2  vols.,  2nd  Edition,  Paris,  F.  Alcan, 

1921,  pp.  xix,  291  ;  288. 

M.  G.  Rigg,  Tneories  of  the  Obligation  of  Citizen  to  State,  Philadelphia, 
University  of  Pennsylvania,  1921,  pp.  75. 


NEW  BOOKS.  377 

R.  E.  Roper,  The  Individual  and  the  Community,  London,  G.  Allen  & 

Unwin  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  224. 

G.  Davy,  La  Foi  Jure'e,  Paris,  F.  Alcan,  1922,  pp.  379. 
J.  Dewey,    Human  Nature  and  Conduct,  London,  G.  Allen  &  Unwin 

Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  vii,  336. 

C.  Lalo,  L'Art  et  la  Morale,  Paris,  F.  Alcan,  1922,  pp.  184. 
F.  Brentano,  Vom  Ursprung  Sittlich  r  Erkenntnis,  2nd  Edition,  ed.  by 

O.  Kraus,  Leipzig,  F.  Meiner,  1922,  pp.  xiv,  108. 
F.  Brentano,  Die  Lehre  J*su  und  ihre  bleibende  Bedeutung,  ed.   by  A. 

Kastil,  Leipzig,  F.  Meiner,  1922,  pp.  xviii,  149. 
J.  R.  Solly,  Free  Will  and  Determinism,  London,  Constable  &  Co.  Ltd., 

1922,  pp.  27. 
F.  C.  Prescott,  The  Poetic  Mind,  New  York,  The  Macmillan  Co.,  1922,  pp. 

xx,  308. 
The  Labour  Movement  and  the   Hospital   Crisis,  London,  The  Trades 

Union  Congress  and  the  Labour  Party,  pp.  20. 
A.  Watkins,  Early  British  Trackways,  Moats,  Mounds,  Camps,  and  Sites, 

Hereford,  The  Watkins  Meter  Co.,  1922,  pp.  40. 


VIII.— PHILOSOPHICAL  PERIODICALS. 

BRITISH  JOURNAL  OF  PSYCHOLOGY.  Vol.  xii.,  Part  i.  June,  1921, 
In  "  Instinctive  Behaviour  and  Enjoyment"  C.  Lloyd  Morgan  discusses 
the  nature  of  instinctive  actions  and  their  dependence  on  heredity.  The 
term  instinctive  is  used  analytically  as  to  that  element  of  a  complex  pro- 
cess which  is  unlearnt.  The  acquisition  of  psychical  data  in  the  process 
of  learning  is  only  "intelligent"  when  such  acquisition  involves  some 
seeking  and  choosing.  The  mere  "provision  and  psychical  registration 
of  data  through  unlearnt  behaviour  does  not  itself  imply  intelligent  pro- 
cesses." The  instinctive  enjoyment  which  is  correlated  with  instinctive 
behaviour  "  is  accompaniment  and  accompaniment  only,  without  guiding 
efficacy,  though  it  provides  the  data  for  conscious  guidance  in  the  life  of 
fuller  and  further  development". 

In  discussing  the  physiological  correlate  of  instinctive  process  the 
author  surmises  that  "intelligent  integration  may  have  its  unlearnt  form 
dependent  on  the  inherited  synaptic  pattern  in  the  cortex".  In  a  con- 
cluding dialogue  Lloyd  Morgan  foreshadows  his  forthcoming  restatement 
of  some  of  Spinoza's  doctrines,  and  in  particular  refers  to  one  corollary  of 
Spinoza's  view  that  there  is  no  interaction  between  instinctive  behaviour 
as  a  mode  within  the  attribute  of  "extension,"  and  instinctive  enjoy- 
ment, as  a  mode  within  the  attribute  of  "thought"  or  of  consciousness. 

F.  Aveling  and  H.  L.  Hargreaves,  in  "Suggestibility  with  and  with- 
out Prestige  in  Children,"  give  an  account  of  experiments  in  two  schools 
with  both  boys  and  girls.  The  tests  included  the  suggestion  of  hand 
rigidity,  of  hand  levitation,  and  of  sense  of  warmth,  of  length  of  lines 
and  of  incorrect  statements  about  pictures  seen.  The  following  conclusions 
were  reached  :  In  cases  of  suggestion,  under  conditions  in  which  the  in- 
fluence of  personal  prestige  was  prominent,  a  negative  response  owing  to 
the  development  of  centra-suggestion  is  frequent.  Consequently  subjects 
tend  to  be  classified  into  two  sharply  divided  groups,  the  suggestible  and 
the  non-suggestible  (or  contra-suggestible).  In  cases  of  impersonal  sug- 
gestion centra-suggestibility  was  not  so  frequently  aroused,  and  the  dis- 
tribution was  approximately  normal,  the  majority  of  the  subjects  being 
moderately  suggestible.  There  was  evidence  which  pointed  to  a  general 
factor  of  Suggestibility  complicated  by  group  factors.  General  suggesti- 
bility was  greatly  modified  by  the  specific  conditions  and  elements  of  the 
whole  situation,  which  vary  in  individual  cases  according  to  experience 
of  it  and  knowledge  about  it.  There  was  no  ascertained  tendency  for 
suggestibility  to  go  with  other  "general  "  factors  such  as  General  Intel- 
ligence, Perseveration,  Oscillation,  or  Motor  Dexterity.  There  was  a 
small  correlation  between  it  and  Common  Sense  regarded  as  consisting 
largely  of  affective  and  conative  elements;  but  none  if  Common  Sense 
was  considered  as  a  purely  cognitive  quality.  B.  Muscio  in  an  article 
"Is  a  Fatigue  Test  possible?"  criticises  the  current  view  of  fatigue  as 
"reduced  capacity  for  work  ".  The  term  work  is  too  narrow  (activity  is 
suggested  as  a  substitute),  yet  is  not  specific  enough  ;  does  it  mean 
capacity  for  the  same  kind  of  work  or  for  all  work  ?  Further  it  takes  no- 


PHILOSOPHICAL  PEEIODICALS.  37$ 

account^of  complication  factors  such  as  varying  incentives  to  work,  the 
effect  of  irrelevant  distractions,  etc.  The  writer  suggests  the  abolition 
of  the  word  fatigue  from  scientific  discussion  and  the  definition  of  such 
problems  in  the  form  of  the  effect  of  different  kinds  and  amounts  of  work 
(activity)  on  mental  and  physiological  functions. 

Other  articles  are  as  follows  : — 

Rodrigo  Lavin,  "  A  Preliminary  Study  of  the  Reproduction  of  Hand 
Movements  ". 

Edward  Bullough,  "Recent  Work  in  Experimental  ^Esthetics  ". 

Q.  Udny  Yule,  "  Critical  Notice  of  William  Brown  and  Godfrey  H. 
Thomson's  *  The  Essentials  of  Mental  Measurement '  ". 

JOURNAL  OP  PHILOSOPHY,  xix.,  3.  C.  H.  Toll.  '  On  the  Method  of 
Metaphysics.'  [All  metaphysics  start  from  the  antithesis  of  the  given 
and  the  real.  The  former  should  have  nothing  hypothetical  about  it,, 
but  in  approaching  the  latter  hypotheses  must  be  used,  and  it  must  not 
be  assumed  that  only  one  of  these  will  be  tenable.  It  is  held  also  that 
"  some  actual  interpreting  of  the  data  is  itself  part  of  the  data  ".  Finally 
metaphysics  should  "give  some  recognition  to  the  non-logical  features  by 
which  some  hypotheses  acquire  a  weighted  value  for  us  "  and  are  selected 
on  moral  or  aesthetic  grounds.]  B.  H.  Bode.  '  Critical  Realism.'  [Argues 
that  the  authors  of  the  book  reviewed  are  not  really  agreed  and  concludes 
that  "Critical  Realism  provides  no  content  for  the  notion  of  mental 
states  ;  which  is  perhaps  the  reason  why  it  is  not  scandalised  by  the  sug- 
gestion of  unconscious  mental  states.  If  we  stick  consistently  to  the 
doctrine  that  the  given  consists  of  essences,  there  can  be  no  room  for 
existences  of  any  sort,  and  both  external  objects  and  mental  states  go  by 
the  board."]  xix.,  4.  K.  Dunlap.  'The  Identity  of  Instinct  and 
Habit.'  [Points  out  that  "the  instincts  are  teleological  groupings  of 
activities,  not  psychological  groupings,"  and  are  based  on  the  purposes  of 
the  classifier  and  not  on  those  of  the  reacting  animal.  In  the  end  there 
is  "no  way  of  distinguishing  usefully  between  instinct  and  habit.  All  re- 
actions are  definite  responses  to  definite  stimulus  patterns,  and  the  exact 
character  of  the  response  is  determined  in  every  case  by  the  inherited 
constitution  of  the  organism  and  the  stimulus  pattern.  All  reactions  are 
instinctive  and  all  are  acquired.  If  we  consider  instinct,  we  find  it  to  be 
the  form  and  method  of  habit-formation  :  if  we  consider  habit  we  find  it 
to  be  the  way  in  which  instinct  exhibits  itself."]  J.  R.  Qeiger.  '  Must 
we  give  up  Instincts  in  Psychology  ?'  [Maintains  that  so  long  as  "the 
primary  condition  of  significant  activity  is  internal  rather  than  external," 
the  term  ( instinct'  is  justified.]  W.  S.  Hunter.  'The  Modification  of 
Instinct.'  [Argues  that  "  associations  formed  prior  to  the  appearance  of 
an  instinct "  may  modify  it  when  it  appears,  without  its  being  therefore 
nothing  but  a  habit.]  xix.,  5.  S.  C.  Pepper.  '  A  Suggestion  Regard- 
ing Esthetics.'  [Three  approaches  to  aesthetics  have  been  tried,  the 
critical,  the  philosophical,  the  psychological ;  none  has  been  a  success. 
But  it  is  not  necessary  that  the  foundations  of  a  science  must  be  firm 
before  it  gets  to  work.  All  a  science  needs  to  start  with  is  a  working, 
unit,  i.e.,  a  working  hypothesis.  The  'liking  a  thing  for  itself  as  op- 
posed to  valuing  it  as  a  means  to  something  else  may  suffice  to  get 
aesthetics  going.]  W.  T.  Bush.  '^Esthetic  Values  and  their  Interpre- 
tation.' [Refuses  to  separate  beauty  and  use  as  sharply  as  the  previous 
paper,  and  suggests  that  beauty  refers  to  present,  use  to  future,  value.] 
A.  L.  Hammond.  'Immediate  Inference  and  the  Distribution  of 
Terms.'  [Denies  that  the  exceptive  proposition  is  adequately  rendered 
by  All  non-S  is  P,  and  the  exclusive  by  All  P  is  S.] 


IX.— NOTES. 
M.  BLONDEL'S  "L'ACTION". 

To  the  Editor  of  "MiND". 

DEAR  SIR, 

I  do  not  think  Prof.  Wildon  Carr  in  his  review  of  the  Italian 
Translation  of  M.  Blondel's  L' Action  can  have  seen  a  letter  of  M.  Blondel 
to  the  March,  1921,  number  of  La  Nouvelle  Journee,  entitled  Un  Rapt. 
Prof.  Wildon  Carr  says  of  the  Italian  Translation,  that  it  was  made 
"against  the  author's  wish,  though  not,  we  understand,  actually  in  defiance 
of  his  authority".  M.  Blondel  in  his  letter  calls  the  translation  "  un 
rapt/'  and  after  a  vigorous  protest — "il  a  suffi  de  1'audace  de  deux 
etrangers  pour  que,  en  depit  des  precautions  les  plus  reflechies  et  contre 
toute  vraisemblance,  un  rapt  soit  commis," — he  quotes  his  letter  to  the 
Editor  and  Translator  of  L' Action;  "Je  proteste  absolument  contre 
1'abus  materiel  et  moral  qui  est  fait  de  mon  ceuvre  et  de  mon  nom.  Au 
mepris  de  mes  droits  les  plus  certains  et  de  mes  intentions  les  plus 
•av^rees,  vous  usurpez  une  'propriete  litteraire,'  qui  ne  vous  appartient  & 
aucun  titre." 

Prof.  Wildon  Carr  also  writes  that  L' Action  "unfortunately  aroused 
such  violent  animosity  in  Catholic  circles  that  the  author  withdrew  it,  and 
so  effectually  that  copies  are  now  excessively  rare  (the  Bodleian  is  believed 
to  be  the  only  public  library  to  possess  one) ".  M.  Blondel  explicitly 
denies  this :  II  est  dit  que  j'ai  retire  mon  livre  du  commerce.  Non  :  les  750 
exemplaires  du  tirage  ont  ete  rapidement  epuises,  rien  de  plus.  Le 
traducteur  donne  en  outre  a  entendre  que  c'est  la  crainte  des  censures  qui 
-a  emp&che  une  rendition.  Non  :  c'est  mon  mecontement  de  moi-meme.  .  .  . 
Copies  of  L' Action  are  rare,  as  the  quotation  given  explains,  but  any 
reader  at  Dr.  Williams'  Library,  for  instance,  could  obtain  one. 

Lastly,  I  think  it  should  be  pointed  out  that  M.  Blondel  would  not 
allow  of  the  association  of  his  name  with  those  of  Bergson,  Croce  and 
Gentile.  His  aims  are  quite  different.  He  has  emphasised  the  funda- 
mental differences  between  Bergson  and  himself,  between  Pragmatism 
And  L' Action,  and  derives  his  inspiration  from  Leibniz  and  O114-Laprune. 

M.  C.  D'ARCY. 


MR.  D'ARCY  is  entirely  right  and  I  must  express  my  sincere  regret  for  the 
error  into  which  I  was  led  by  an  Italian  friend  of  the  translator  at  the 
time  of  the  publication  of  the  translation  last  summer. 

The  association  of  M.  Blondel's  name  with  Bergson,  Croce,  and  Gentile 
was  not  intended  to  convey  the  idea  that  their  aims  were  identical.  My 
reference  was  not  personal  at  all  but  meant  only  to  indicate  a  tendency  of 
•doctrines  in  themselves  totally  diverse. 

H.  WILDON  CARR. 


NOTES.  381 

INTUITION  OF  REALITY. 

Sra, 

Mr.  Leo  Stein  relates  in  the  April  number  of  MIND  an  experi- 
ence which  he  believes  to  be  similar  to  my  own  experience  of  an  ineradi- 
cable certainty  of  the  immortality,  pre-existence  and  bisexuality  of  the  Self. 
I  am  afraid  his  vision  which  gave  him  the  explanation  of  rest  and  motion, 
was  of  a  totally  different  kind.  It  did  not  refer  to  his  own  innermost 
Self,  and  did  not  give  him  a  permanent  absolute  conviction,  with  many 
practical  consequences  in  everyday  life,  as  was  the  case  with  me.  The 
fact  that  he  could  attempt  later  to  explain  it  away  by  the  very  unconvinc- 
ing image  of  a  balloon  which  may  burst  and  disappear,  proves  clearly  that 
he  did  not  reach  absolute  reality.  I  quite  agree  with  him  that  if  he  had 
the  impression  that  he  was  whatever  he  thought,  this  was  not  sound 
knowledge.  I  know  myself  to  be  myself,  and  different  from  everybody 
else.  Such  a  knowledge  remains  unshaken  for  ever,  and  cannot  be  ex- 
plained away  as  an  illusion.  I  trust  that  some  readers  of  MIND  have  ex- 
perienced the  birth  of  such  a  conviction  which  cannot  be  shaken  by  any- 
thing. Their  testimony  would  confirm,  but  could  not  strengthen,  my  own 
conviction  that  I  am  a  true  Being,  which  cannot  be  destroyed  by  Death 
and  has  not  been  created  by  conception  and  birth.  I  remember  a  very 
long  conversation  with  William  James  on  this  subject  in  1899  and  learn 
that  in  his  published  correspondence  a  letter  from  him  to  Miss  Frances 
R.  Morse  of  17th  September,  1899,  is  printed  in  which  he  writes  with 
reference  to  this  meeting  at  Bad  Nauheim  : — 

' '  He  takes  in  dead  seriousness  what  most  people  admit,  but  only  half 
believe,  viz.,  that  we  are  Souls,  that  souls  are  immortal  and  agents  of  the 
world's  destinies,  and  that  the  chief  concern  of  a  Soul  is  to  get  ahead  by 
the  help  of  other  souls  with  whom  it  can  establish  confidential  relations 
.  .  .  abstractly  his  scheme  is  divine,  but  there  is  something  on  which  I 
can't  yet  lay  my  defining  finger  that  makes  one  feel  that  there  is  ecvme 
need  of  the  corrective  and  critical  and  arresting  judgment  in  his  manner 
of  carrying  it  out.  These  Slavs  seem  to  be  the  great  radical  livers-out 
of  their  theories." 

William  James  was  right  in  thinking  that  there  was  something  wrong 
in  my  way  of  carrying  out  the  consequences  of  my  conviction.  I  believed 
that  everybody  can  go  through  the  same  experience  and  I  was  wrong. 
Since  then  I  have  learnt  that  such  an  experience  is  rare  and  that  it  cannot 
be  produced  by  the  influence  of  one  man  on  another.  It  must  come  un- 
sought and  not  by  some  kind  of  suggestion,  if  it  is  to  leave  lasting  results. 

Yours  sincerely, 
W.  LUTOSLAWSKI. 


SIR  HENRY  JONES,  C.H.,  LL.D.,  D.LITT.,  F.B.A.,  1852-1922. 

WITH  the  death  of  Sir  Henry  Jones,  on  4th  February,  1922,  philosophy 
loses  one  of  the  band  of  brilliant  men  who  studied  philosophy  under 
Caird  in  Glasgow.  Sir  Henry  Jones,  the  son  of  a  shoemaker,  fought  his 
way  through  poverty  from  shoemaking  to  the  University,  with  no  advan- 
tages but  those  due  to  an  indomitable  spirit,  and  the  proud  and  loving 
help  of  the  village  community  in  which  he  was  brought  up.  He  occupied 
the  Chair  of  Philosophy  and  Political  Economy  in  Bangor,  North  Wales, 
and  the  Chair  of  Logic  in  St.  Andrews  ;  and  in  1894  was  appointed  as 
Caird's  successor  to  the  Chair  of  Moral  Philosophy  in  Glasgow.  His 
writings  include  Browning  as  a  Philosophical  and  Religious  Teacher 


382  NOTES. 

(1891)  ;  The  Philosophy  of  Lotze  (1895)  ;  Social  Responsibilities  (1905)  ; 
Idealism  as  a  Practical  Creed  (1909),  delivered  in  the  University  of 
Sydney,  New  South  Wales  ;  Social  Powers  (1913)  ;  The  Principles  of 
Citizenship  (1919) ;  A  Faith  that  Enquires  (1922),  Gifford  Lectures  de- 
livered in  the  University  of  Glasgow,  1920-1921.  With  Prof.  J.  H.  Muir- 
Lead  he  wrote  the  Life  of  Edward  Caird  (1922). 

Philosophy  in  his  hands  was  something  vital.  He  drove  it  unceasingly 
on  to  the  practical  issues  of  life,  and  brought  the  practical  issues  back  to 
ultimate  principles  of  metaphysics.  Plato  and  Aristotle,  Spinoza  and 
Kant  and  Hegel,  and  with  them,  Nettleship  and  Green,  Caird  and 
Wallace,  were  his  favourite  philosophers  :  for  in  them  he  felt  a  centrality 
of  outlook,  a  Tightness  of  spirit,  which  seemed  to  him  lacking  in  Descartes 
or  Leibniz,  Locke  or  Hume.  His  books  show  how  much  his  thought  and 
his  style  owed  to  the  Bible  and  to  the  great  poets.  His  weightiest  book 
is  his  Lotze,  but  he  did  not  complete  the  promised  sequel,  largely,  I 
believe,  because  he  felt  that  the  investigation  would  not  be  as  valuable  as 
.a  more  direct  and  positive  exposition  of  the  conclusions  to  which  a 
criticism  of  Lotze  would  have  led. 

This  attitude  was  due  to  the  intensity  of  his  feeling  that  a  true  phil- 
osophy is  so  urgent  a  matter  for  life  that  you  cannot  afford  to  delay  too 
long  over  positions  which  have  already  been  discovered  to  rest  on 
erroneous  principles.  To  follow  out  in  detail  the  consequences  of  prin- 
ciples which  rest  on  wrong  assumptions  is,  he  felt,  to  fritter  away 
energy  which  it  is  a  duty  to  put  to  more  fruitful  uses.  He  taught  his 
students  to  endeavour  to  bring  to  light  the  hidden  assumptions  on  which 
any  philosophy  rests,  and  to  concentrate  on  them,  because  they  are  the 
important  part  of  the  philosophy.  When  you  have  learned,  he  insisted, 
go  forward  and  leave  the  mistakes  behind.  The  task  appeared  to 
him  less  tortuous  and  complex  than  it  appeared  to  some  of  his  men  ; 
where  he  was  sure,  they  were  groping  slowly  and  in  uncertainty  ;  but 
the;-  could  not  fail  to  be  penetrated  by  his  spirit  of  the  seriousness  of  the 
task  undertaken  by  philosophy. 

He  was  a  keen  fighter  and  a  great  friend.  There  was  nothing  half- 
Jiearted  or  moderate  about  him.  True  virtue,  he  insisted,  can  let  itself  go, 
fully  and  absolutely,  for  it  is  infinite  and  (it  was  a  central  thought)  carries 
its  own  limits  within  it  as  a  part  of  itself.  And  he  pointed  to  the  life  of 
Christ. 

This  big-hearted  outspoken  optimism  was,  I  think,  the  source  of  the 
great  parsonal  influence  he  exerted.  It  was  the  source,  too,  of  the  some- 
what mixed  feelings  some  of  his  students  had  for  him.  When  you  felt  he 
was  going  rather  rapidly  to  his  conclusions,  putting  aside  with  a  gesture 
obstacles  that  you  felt  were  stronger  than  he  would  allow,  he  would  bear 
down  on  you  and  the  obstacle  with  his  scorn,  reducing  you  to  silence. 
And  then,  as  if  he  saw  you  felt  he  was  bullying,  he  would  pull  himself  up 
;and  try  to  make  amends  by  mildness. 

His  Gifford  Lectures  were  completed  during  a  last  gallant  struggle 
against  the  disease  which  he  had  fought  so  cheerfully  for  many  years. 
He  lost  his  much  loved  younger  son  in  the  war.  It  was  given  to  him  to 
enact  in  his  own  person  the  tragedy  that,  in  his  younger  and  vigorous 
days,  had  always  seemed  to  him  to  be  the  most  sublime  expression  of 
Tiumanity's  faith,  and  to  be  able  himself,  in  his  own  tragedy,  to  keep  his 
faith  undimmed.  "  Though  He  slay  me,  yet  will  I  trust  Him,"  he  could 
still  say. 

LEONARD  RUSSELL. 


NOTES.  383 

THE  LATE  MISS  E.  E.  CONSTANCE  JONES. 

Miss  JONES  rendered  services  of  very  high  value  and  importance  to 
education  as  Lecturer  in  Logic  at  Gerton,  and  subsequently  as  mistress 
of  that  College.  She  was  also  endeared  to  a  large  circle  of  friends  and 
pupils  by  her  rare  and  admirable  personal  character.  It  would  require 
much  space  to  do  justice  to  her  memory  from  these  points  of  view.  What 
I  am  here  especially  concerned  with  is  her  published  work  in  Philosophy. 
Mtss  Jones  was  keenly  interested  in  all  vital  philosophical  questions  and 
she  has  written  well  on  Ethics  and  Metaphysics.  Logic,  however,  was 
her  special  subject,  and  it  is  only  here  that  she  would  herself  have  made 
any  claim  to  originality.  The  logical  topics  with  which  she  was  chiefly 
concerned  were  the  import  and  interpretation  of  propositions.  She  did 
good  service  in  insisting  on  the  distinction  between  interpretation  from 
the  point  of  view  of  the  speaker  and  that  of  the  hearer.  But  her  main 
contribution,  in  her  own  view  and  also  in  mine,  is  to  be  found  in  her 
general  view  of  import.1  On  the  threshold  of  Logic  we  are  confronted  by 
the  question,  What  is  a  proposition  ?  and  this,  as  Miss  Jones  maintained, 
is  identical  with  the  question,  "  What  is  a  significant  assertion  ? "  There 
is  significance  so  far  and  only  so  far  as  thought  is  carried  forward  beyond 
its  point  of  departure  to  something  in  some  way  different  from  this. 
Thus  the  verbal  formula  A  is  A  is  totally  insignificant.  On  the  other 
hand,  mere  difference  is  not  enough  to  give  significance.  In  asserting  a 
proposition  we  always  assert  identity  :  to  say  that  A  is  B  is  to  say  that 
what  we  distinguish  as  being  A,  is  identical  with  something  that  is  B.  This 
cannot,  of  course,  mean  that  differences  as  such  are  identical.  Are  we 
then  to  say,  with  many  logicians,  that  what  is  asserted  is  "  identity  in 
difference  "  ?  But  how  can  this  be,  if  the  differences  themselves  are  not 
identical  ?  Miss  Jones  holds  that  we  ought  to  speak  of  differences  within 
an  identity  rather  than  of  identity  in  difference.  In  ordinary  categorical 
propositions  we  are  dealing  with  a  complex  unity,  comprehending  and 
connecting  with  each  other,  on  the  one  hand,  a  character  specifying  this 
complex  as  the  subject  concerning  which  an  assertion  is  made,  on  the  other 
hand,  a  character  asserted  as  predicate.  The  copula  is  the  c  >mplex  unity 
itself.  Miss  Jones  further  identifies  the  inclusive  whole  with  "denota- 
tion" and  the  diverse  characters  which  it  includes  with  "intension". 
Every  categorical  affirmation  asserts  diversity  of  intension  as  included 
within  a  denotational  unity.  In  S  is  P,  the  denotation  of  S  and  P  is  the 
same  though  S-ness  and  P-ness  are  diverse.  As  a  general  formula  for 
categoricals  this  seems  fairly  satisfactory,  though  not  entirely  free  from 
difficulty.  But  Miss  Jones  would  also  extend  it  to  hypothetical  and 
disjunctive  propositions.  Though  she  defends  this  position  with  much 
acuteness  and  ingenuity,  it  can  hardly  be  said  that  her  treatment  of  the 
question  is  adequate.  Granting  that  in  non-categoricals  as  in  categoricals 
what  is  asserted  is  always  the  connexion  of  differences  within  a  unity  ;  it 
is  not  clear  that  this  can  be  adequately  described  as  a  denotational  unity, 
when  the  meaning  of  the  word  denotation  is  determined  merely  by  the 
current  use  of  it  in  logical  text-book.  Further  analysis  and  reconstruc- 
tion seem  to  be  required.  However  this  may  be,  MISS  Jones  was,  I 
think,  right  in  insisting  that  some  explicit  formula  defining  the  most 
general  conditions  of  significant  assertion  ought  to  be  made  fundamental 
in  works  on  Logic. 

1Most  definitely  formulated  in  her  little  book  A  New  Law  of  Thought 
and  Its  Logical  Bearings,  which  was  very  appreciatively  reviewed  by  Dr. 
Schiller,  MIND,  N.S.,  vol.  xxi.,  p.  246.  Cf.,  Symposium  in  Aristot.  Soc. 
Proceedings,  1914-1915,  p.  353. 


384  NOTES. 

I  have  dwelt  on  this  topic,  because  Miss  Jones  herself  would  have 
wished  me  to  do  so.  Her  work  on  other  subjects  than  Logic,  though  highly 
competent,  was  expository  and  critical  rather  than  constructive.  In 
Ethics  she  has  given  a  very  accurate  and  careful  account  of  Sidgwick's 
utilitarianism  and  an  able  defence  of  it  against  its  critics.1  She  showed 
her  interest  in  Metaphysics  by  her  admirably  accurate  and  lucid  transla- 
tion of  Lotze's  Microcosmus.  I  may  also  refer  to  an  article  on  "Dr. 
Ward's  Refutation  of  Dualism  "  as  a  good  sample  of  her  power  of  exposi- 
tion and  sympathetic  appreciation.2 

No  mere  reference  to  her  published  work  will  do  justice  to  the  service 
rendered  by  Miss  Jones  to  philosophy  within  her  own  circle  of  friends 
and  colleagues.  In  conversation  and  discussion  she  was  in  a  high  degree 
helpful  and  stimulating,  owing  to  her  keen  and  unfailing  interest  in 
philosophical  questions,  her  candour  and  straight-forward  simplicity,  and 
her  remarkable  flashes  of  insight. 

G.  F.  STOUT. 


SOCIETAS  SPINOZANA. 

AN  international  society  with  this  title  and  having  its  headquarters  at 
The  Hague  was  founded  in  1920  in  order  to  further  the  study  of  Spinoza's 
philosophy.  With  this  object  it  proposes,  among  other  things,  to  publish 
annually  a  journal,  to  be  called  Chronicon  Spinozanum,  containing 
articles,  in  various  languages,  bearing  on  Spinoza's  teaching  and  life  ;  and 
the  first  number  of  this  journal  is  now  ready.  The  editors  are  H. 
Hoffding,  W.  Meyer,  Sir  F.  Pollock,  L.  Brunschvieg  and  C.  Gebhardt. 
The  journal  will  not  be  on  sale  to  the  general  public,  but  members  of  the 
society  will  receive  it  free  of  charge  ;  and  applications  for  membership 
are  invited.  Members  must  be  approved  by  the  Governing  Body  of  the 
society  and  must  pay  an  annual  subscription  of  10s.  Application  may  be 
made  to  Mr.  L.  Roth,  Exeter  College,  Oxford. 

1  Proceedings  of  Aristot.  Society,  1903-1905. 

2  MIND,  N.S.,  vol.  ix. 


VOL.  xxxi.     No.   124.]  [OCTOBER,   1922. 

*-&s 


MIND 


A  QUARTERLY  REVIEW 

OF 

PSYCHOLOGY  AND  PHILOSOPHY 


I.— PROF.  ALEXANDER'S  THEORY  OF  SENSE 
PERCEPTION.1,2 

BY  G.  F.  STOUT. 
THE  PKOBLEM. 

THERE  is  a  system  of  things  and  events  which  exist,  endure, 
change  and  interact  independently  of  the  conditions  which 
make  them  perceptible  to  us  through  sense  experience.  This 
we  may  call  the  physical  world.  It  contains  our  own  bodies 
and  also  things  external  to  our  bodies  which  we  may  call 
external  objects.  In  agreement  with  Mr.  Alexander  and  also 
with  common  sense  and  science,  I  take  the  existence  of  the 
physical  world  for  granted.  We  are  concerned  only  with  the 
question  how  we  know  it  in  sense  perception. 

Ordinary  sense  perception  includes  much  knowledge  which 
is  due  to  previous  perceptions,  as  when  we  say  that  we  hear 
a  footstep  on  the  stair  or  a  horse  trotting.  But  there  is  also 
in  all  sense  perception  a  factor  that  cannot  be  accounted  for 
in  this  way.  There  is  a  modification  of  the  content  of  sense 
experience  which  occurs  independently  of  any  reinstatement 
from  the  past.  This  factor  is  present  alike  in  normal  per- 
ception and  in  dreams,  hallucinations  and  illusions.  When 
a  drunkard  seems  to  see  pink  rats,  he  is  really  aware  of  an 
actual  sense-apparition  such  as  would  be  normally  experienced 
if  there  were  really  pink  rats  before  his  eyes. 

1  Contributed  to  the  Joint  Session  of  the  Mind  Association  and  Aris- 
totelian Society  at  Manchester,  July  14th-16th,  1922. 

2  Throughout  this  paper  I  have  criticised  Mr.   Alexander's  theory  of 
knowledge  in  an  unsparing  way.     I  feel  bound,  therefore,  to  say  once  for 
all,  that  I  immensely  admire  the  ability  and  thoroughness  with  which  he 
has  attempted  to  maintain  what  I  regard  as  a  quite  untenable  doctrine. 
No  one,  I   think,  could  have  performed  better  the  task  which  he  has 
undertaken  ;  and  we  owe  him  a  great  debt  of  gratitude  for  putting  us  in 
an  advantageous  position  for  judging  a  view  which  must  be  either  accepted 
or  rejected  before  further  advance  can  be  made. 

25 


386  a.  F.  STOUT: 

These  contents  of  immediate  sense  experience  must  not  be 
confused  with  our  knowing  about  them.  We  recognise  and 
distinguish  them  ;  we  attend  to  them,  like  or  dislike  them, 
desire  their  presence  or  absence.  But  they  are  not  themselves 
recognitions  or  distinctions,  likings  or  dislikings  or  desires. 

They  are  or  may  be  objects  for  a  subject  but  are  not  them- 
selves subjective.  We  have  not  a  right  to  regard  them  as 
mental  in  any  sense  in  which  what  is  mental  is  contrasted 
with  what  is  material.  In  agreement  with  Alexander,  I 
should  myself  maintain  that  in  the  antithesis  of  matter  and 
mind  they  fall  on  the  side  of  matter  and  not  of  mind. 

I  use  the  term  sensum  rather  than  sensation  because 
"sensation"  almost  inevitably  suggests  something  dis- 
tinctively mental,  and  may  lead  to  confusion  between  know- 
ing and  experiencing  on  the  one  hand,  and  what  we  know 
or  experience  on  the  other.  It  is,  in  fact,  open  to  the  same 
objection  as  Berkeley's  use  of  the  wrord  "idea"  which  gave 
rise  to  the  gravest  misunderstanding  of  his  real  meaning. 
Instead  of  sensation  the  term  "sense-datum"  has  been  em- 
ployed by  recent  writers.  But  this  also  is  a  question-begging 
word.  It  suggests  that  what  we  originally  know  in  sense 
perception  is  merely  the  sense  apparition  as  immediately 
experienced  to  the  exclusion  of  anything  beyond  it.  This 
assumption  seems  to  be  a  mere  superstition,  which  would 
make  knowledge  of  the  physical  world  impossible.  I,  there- 
fore, prefer  the  term  "  sensum  "  which  is  also  used  by  Mr. 
Alexander.  I  prefer  it  because  it  does  not  prejudge  the  view 
that  though  knowledge  is  limited  by  immediate  experience  it 
is  not  even  originally  limited  to  immediate  experience. 

It  is  here  that  my  disagreement  with  Mr.  Alexander  begins. 
He  seems  to  hold  that  sense  perception  is  primarily  confined 
to  sensa.  His  peculiar  theory  of  sense  knowledge  is  an  at- 
tempt to  show  how  on  this  assumption,  we  can,  none  the 
less,  know  by  way  of  sense  a  world  of  physical  things  and 
events. 

ME.  ALEXANDER'S  GENERAL  THEORY. 

According  to  Alexander,  all  knowledge  is  the  direct  revela- 
tion to  the  knowing  mind  of  something  which  exists  inde- 
pendently of  being  known.  This  is  a  position  which  I  myself 
accept.  I  disagree  only  with  his  application  of  it  to  sensa 
and  images.  Here  we  are  concerned  especially  with  sensa. 
He  asserts  and  I  deny  that  sensa  are  identical  with  perceived 
features  of  physical  existence. 

A  convenient  way  of  approaching  the  question  is  by  con- 
sidering the  connexion  of  sensa  with  those  processes  in  the 
percipient's  body  without  which  they  are  not  experienced. 


PEOF.  ALEXANDERS  THEORY  OF  SENSE  PERCEPTION.   387 

It  is,  I  take  it,  generally  admitted  that  there  is  no  variation 
in  the  sensa  without  corresponding  variations  in  the  bodily 
conditions,  and  no  variation  in  relevant  bodily  conditions  with- 
out corresponding  variations  in  the  sensa.  Factors  external  to 
the  body  make  no  difference  to  the  sensum,  unless  and  so  far 
as  they  affect  the  sense  organ,  and  processes  in  the  sense 
organ  make  no  difference  unless  and  so  far  as  they  affect  the 
nervous  system. 

Facts  of  this  sort  naturally  point  to  the  view  that  sensa 
have  no  existence  apart  from  the  percipient's  organism,  and 
that  what  occurs  outside  the  nervous  system  makes  no  differ- 
ence to  them,  except  in  so  far  as  it  makes  a  difference  to  this. 
The  sensum  can  no  more  be  identical  with  all  or  any  of  the 
external  factors  concerned  in  the  production  of  the  physio- 
logical process  than  this  process  itself  can  be  identical  with 
its  external  conditions. 

This  is  the  natural  view  suggested  primd  facie  by  the 
facts.  But  Mr.  Alexander  thinks  that  the  facts  can  be  other- 
wise construed,  and  he  holds  that  they  must  be  otherwise 
construed  if  we  are  to  give  any  tenable  account  of  our  know- 
ledge of  the  physical  world.  His  own  theory  may  be  called 
the  penny -in-the-slot  theory.  According  to  him,  when  we 
perceive  objects  as  external  to  our  sense  organs  the  sensum 
is  itself  a  feature  of  the  external  object,  having  an  existence 
and  nature  of  its  own,  quite  independent  of  its  entrance  into 
our  sense  experience,  whereby  it  becomes  a  sensum.  The 
physical  and  physiological  conditions  of  perception  simply 
serve  to  unveil  it.  They  put  a  penny  in  the  slot  and  so,  as  it 
were,  remove  a  screen  which  would  otherwise  have  hidden  it 
from  the  percipient. 

In  looking  at  a  sheet  of  white  paper,  I  experience  a 
sensum  having  a  certain  shape  and  colour  quality.  Alexander 
holds  that  under  normal  conditions,  this  very  shape  and 
quality,  as  I  immediately  experience  them,  pre-existed  in  the 
paper  before  I  saw  it,  and  continue  to  exist  when  I  cease  to 
see  it.  They  exist  in  the  paper  whether  anyone  sees  it  or 
not,  and  might  have  so  existed  if  there  had  been  no  eyes  or 
brains  in  the  world.  The  passage  of  reflected  light  from  the 
paper  to  the  eye  and  the  ensuing  processes  in  the  retina  and 
brain  determine  only  the  appearing  of  the  sense  apparition. 
They  in  no  way  determine  the  existence  or  nature  of  that 
which  is  thus  revealed.  In  this  example  there  is  a  continuous 
train  of  processes  constituting  what  may  be  called  a  bridge 
between  the  perceived  physical  existence  at  one  end  and  at 
the  other  the  neural  occurrences  which  are  more  directly 
connected  with  the  relevant  sense  experience.  Further,  the 
bridging  series  of  events  is  causally  initiated  from  the  side  ol 


388  G.  F.  STOUT: 

the  thing  perceived  and  not  from  the  side  of  the  subject. 
What  occurs  to  the  percipient's  brain  is  only  a  terminal  effect. 
But  this  is  not  what  happens  in  ideal  revivals,  dreams, 
illusions  and  hallucinations.  When  for  instance,  we  look  at 
a  grey  speck  on  a  red  ground  and,  owing  to  contrast,  experi- 
ence a  green  sensum  instead  of  a  grey  one,  what  is  revealed 
as  a  sensum  is  some  particular  green  existing  in  a  place  and 
at  a  time  other  than  the  place  and  time  of  the  grey  speck. 
The  green  depends  on  the  reflexion  of  light  from  the  surface 
of  some  independently  existing  thing.  But  the  reflected 
light  is  not  propagated  to  the  eyes  of  the  percipient.  How 
then  is  the  connexion  established  when  the  green  is  sensibly 
revealed  to  him  ?  Mr.  Alexander  answers  that  the  process 
which  unveils  the  sensum  may  be  initiated  in  two  ways.  In 
veridical  perception,  it  is  initiated  from  the  side  of  the  per- 
ceived object.  In  dreams,  illusions,  hallucinations  and  also 
in  ideal  revival,  it  is  initiated  from  the  side  of  the  subject. 
There  is  simply  an  inversion  of  what  is  otherwise,  in  all 
relevant  respects,  the  same  train  of  events.1 

Mr.  Alexander  does  not  anywhere  attempt  to  deny  that 
sense  apparitions  come  and  go  and  vary  in  strict  correspond- 
ence with  events  happening  in  the  sense  organs  and  nervous 
system  just  as  if,  not  only  their  appearance,  but  their  nature 
and  existence  were  inseparable  from  such  bodily  conditions. 
From  this  point  of  view,  therefore,  all  that  he  can  be  logic- 
ally justified  in  asserting  is  that  his  own  revelation  theory  is 
a  possible  alternative  which  may  also  be  made  to  fit  the 
facts.  Instead  of  proceeding  in  this  way,  he  presses  his  own 
dictum  upon  us  as  that  which  we  must  accept  to  the  ex- 
clusion of  any  other.  Before  proceeding  to  detailed  criticism, 
it  will  be  useful  to  consider  the  motives  which  have  led  him 
to  take  up  a  position  so  uncompromising. 

THE  MOTIVES  WHICH  UNDEELIE  HIS  THEOEY. 

He  certainly  does  not  prefer  his  own  theory  on  the  ground 
that  it  is  simpler.  On  the  contrary,  he  frankly  admits  that 
it  is  much  more  complicated  and  difficult.  "  I  cannot,"  he 
says,  "  help  confessing  how  much  simpler  it  would  be,  and 
how  much  laborious  explanation  it  would  save,  if  only  it 
were  true  that  our  intuitions  and  sensations  were  mental, 
as  is  commonly  supposed,  and  how  easy  it  is  compared  with 
our  procedure  to  refer  "  their  "variations  in  part  to  the  mind 
or  its  body".2  His  reason  for  refusing  to  follow  this  easy 
road  is  that  it  leads  to  destruction.  "We  should  be  living 

1 1  shall  try  to  show  at  the  close  of  this  paper  that  there  is  no  such 
initiation  from  the  side  of  the  subject. 
2  Space,  Time,  and  Deity,  vol.  ii.,  p.  199. 


PROF.  ALEXANDEK'S  THEORY  OF  SENSE  PERCEPTION.    389 

in  a  world  of  sensations  which  would  be  hallucinations  .  .  . ; 
some  would  be  veridical  and  some  not.  But  we  could  only 
discriminate  the  veridical  ones  by  means  of  sensation,  that 
is,  by  other  hallucinations.  For  it  is  of  no  use  to  urge  that 
our  appearances  are  partly  determined  by  the  thing  and 
partly  by  our  bodies.  How  shall  we  know  what  part  is  due 
to  things  except  through  observation,  for  which,  in  turn,  we 
are  dependent  in  part  upon  our  bodies?  We  are  reduced 
to  a  world  of  consistent  hallucination."1  In  this  passage 
Alexander  treats  as  equivalent  two  entirely  distinct  propo- 
sitions :  (1)  that  sensa  and  images  are  mental,  and  (2)  that 
they  are  directly  correlated  in  their  existence  and  nature 
with  occurrences  in  the  body  of  the  percipient.  I  admit  and 
maintain  that  if  they  were  not  material  but  mental  we  could 
not  know  anything  about  a  material  world.  We  should  not 
even  have  the  thought  of  such  a  world  so  as  to  be  able  to 
raise  the  question  whether  it  exists  or  not.  If,  through 
sense  perception,  we  are  to  know  about  the  moon  as  it  exists 
independently  of  our  sensitive  organism,  the  sensum  which 
we  have  in  seeing  it  must  be  continuous  in  existence  with 
it,  and  therefore  fundamentally  homogeneous  with  it  in  its 
general  nature.  The  contents  of  sense  experience  and 
physical  facts  must  belong  to  the  same  order  of  being  and 
be  contained  within  the  unity  of  the  same  continuous  whole. 
Just  as,  within  the  sense  experience  of  each  individual,  his 
several  sensa  are  variable  modifications  of  one  presentation 
continuum,  so  the  several  presentation  continua  of  each  of 
us  are  all  continued  into  and  are  of  a  piece  with  a  wider 
continuum  which  comprehends  and  connects  them — compre- 
hends and  connects  them  as  the  physical  universe  compre- 
hends and  connects  your  body  and  mine.  It  will  be  said 
that  even  if,  in  fact,  sensa  are  thus  prolonged  into  an  exist- 
ence beyond  themselves,  yet,  since  this  existence  is  not 
immediately  experienced,  we  can  never  come  to  know  that 
it  exists  or  of  what  nature  it  is.  It  is  of  vital  importance  to 
note  at  the  outset  that  this  supposed  difficulty  arises  from  the 
assumption  that  in  sense  knowledge  all  that  we  know 
primarily  and  immediately  is  what  from  time  to  time  we 
immediately  experience  as  a  sensum.  On  this  basis  it  is 
cogently  argued  that  if  we  start  merely  with  these  immediate 
sensa,  there  is  no  assignable  way  of  passing  beyond  them. 
Hence,  if  they  are  not  themselves  features  of  the  physical 
world  existing  apart  from  the  conditions  under  which  they 
appear  to  us,  it  is  impossible  that  we  should  ever  come  to 
know,  or  even  have  any  thought  of  physical  objects  at  all. 

1  tipace,  Time,  and  Deity,  vol.  ii.,  p.  199. 


390  G.   F.    STOUT  : 

As  Dr.  Hutcheson  Stirling  puts  it :  "  How  can  the  scratch 
know  of  the  thorn  ?  "  Granting  the  initial  assumption,  this 
reasoning  seems  incontrovertible.  But  if  we  concede  the 
initial  assumption,  I  do  not  see  how  Alexander's  theory  of 
perception  can  remove  the  resulting  difficulty.  Whether  sensa 
are  or  are  not  features  of  the  world  existing  apart  from  our 
sense  organs  and  nervous  system,  they  form  at  any  rate  only 
a  vanishingly  small  fragment  of  this  world  as  known  to 
common  sense  in  its  spatial  and  temporal  immensity,  and 
its  microscopic  complexity.  If  this  tiny  bit  is  all  that  is 
primarily  known  how  are  we  to  pass  from  it  to  a  knowledge 
of  the  rest?  Further,  even  the  given  fragment  lacks  the 
internal  coherence  of  the  material  world.  Sensa,  considered 
merely  as  they  occur  within  individual  experience,  have  no 
systematic  order  according  to  general  rules,  such  as  makes 
possible  our  daily  lives.  Berkeley,  Mill,  and  Mr.  Eussell,  in 
order  to  obtain  such  an  order,  have  to  posit,  besides  actual 
sensa,  a  vast  system  of  possibilities  of  sensation,  conceived 
as  existing,  persisting,  changing,  and  mutually  determining 
each  other  as  if  they  were  not  mere  possibilities  but  actual 
existences.  But  if  we  start  purely  and  merely  from  sensa 
as  they  are  actually  sensed,  and  images  as  they  are  actually 
imaged,  we  cannot  even  reach  such  a  system  of  possibilities : 
and  if  we  could,  we  should  not  be  able  to  define  what  the 
system  is  without  presupposing  a  system  of  actual  existences 
other  than  the  sensa  themselves,  on  which  it  depends — in- 
cluding our  own  bodies  and  the  things  around  us,  near  and 
remote.  If  we  grant  to  Mr.  Alexander  that  sensa  are  merely 
disclosures  within  our  experience  of  independently  existing 
features  of  the  physical  world,  and  that  therefore  they  cannot 
be  hallucinations,  yet  if  these  sensa  are  all  that  we  know, 
they  cannot  for  us  constitute  a  world. 

But  does  Mr.  Alexander  really  assume  that  our  knowledge 
is  primarily  confined  to  the  contents  of  immediate  experience  ? 
The  answer  is  that  sometimes  he  does  and  sometimes  he  does 
not.  The  term  "experience  "  is  loose  and  ambiguous;  and 
Mr.  Alexander  seems  to  pass  from  one  meaning  of  it  to 
another  without  noting  the  difference.  Sometimes,  the  word 
is  used  for  all  knowledge  as  dependent  on  experience,  as 
having  its  source  in  experience,  as  limited  and  conditioned 
by  the  limitations  and  conditions  of  experience.  Sometimes 
it  is  used  for  the  experience  itself  in  which  knowledge  has 
its  source,  and  by  which  it  is  conditioned  and  therefore 
limited.  A  dentist's  knowledge  that  his  patient  is  feeling 
toothache  doubtless  has  its  source  in  experience  in  the 
narrower  sense  of  the  word.  What  is  thus  known  may 


PROF.  ALEXANDER'S  THEORY  OF  SENSE  PERCEPTION.    391 

therefore  be  said  to  come  within  the  range  of  his  experience 
— in  the  wider  sense.  But,  in  the  narrower  sense,  he 
certainly  does  not  experience  his  patient's  toothache.  He 
can  experience  only  his  own  toothache.  He  can  know  about 
his  patient's  pain ;  but  he  cannot,  as  Mr.  Russell  would  say, 
be  immediately  acquainted  with  it.  To  avoid  the  ambiguity, 
I  am  in  the  habit  of  calling  experience  in  the  narrower  sense, 
immediate  experience.  But  Mr.  Alexander  does  not  attempt 
to  avoid  the  ambiguity.  It  continually  brings  grist  to  his 
mill  and  alone  makes  his  theory  of  knowledge  seem  plausible. 
This  fundamental  confusion  is  found  even  in  his  general 
account  of  primary  sense  perception.  Primarily,  according 
to  him,  what  is  experienced  is  the  sensum,  and  the  sensum 
is  a  feature  of  the  physical  world  existing  quite  independently 
of  the  conditions  under  which  we  experience  it — existing 
before  and  continuing  to  exist  after  its  appearance  to  us. 
But  besides  this  he  always  assumes,  tacitly  or  explicitly, 
not  only  that  this  independent  existence  is  a  fact,  but  that 
the  fact  is  immediately  known  in  sense-knowledge.  I  grant 
that  if  it  is  to  be  known  at  all,  it  must  be  immediately  known,1 
But  it  does  not  follow  that  what  is  immediately  known  must 
be  immediately  experienced.  How  can  we  immediately  ex- 
perience the  fact  that  something  existed  before  it  was  im- 
mediately experienced  and  will  exist  after  it  has  ceased  to  be 
so,  and  that  its  existence  is  independent  of  its  occurrence  as 
a  sense  apparition?  How  can  such  facts  be  immediately 
experienced  as  the  sensum  itself  is  ?  If  knowledge  of  this 
sort  is  to  be  called  experience,  it  can  be  so  only  in  the  wider 
and  looser  application  of  the  word.  It  is,  of  course,  open  to 
Mr.  Alexander  to  say  that  what  I  have  called  the  wider  and 
looser  application  is  the  only  one  that  is  important,  and  that 
the  distinction  between  what  we  immediately  experience  and 
what  we  know  through  experience  makes  no  difference  to 
his  account  of  the  way  in  which  we  know  the  external  world. 
But  if  he  proceeds  on  this  principle,  he  ought  to  do  so  con- 
sistently. He  has  no  right  to  ignore  a  distinction  in  working 
out  his  own  views,  and  also  to  use  this  very  distinction  as  a 
weapon  against  those  who  disagree  with  him.  Yet  this  is 
precisely  what  he  does,  as  may  be  shown  by  a  further 
quotation  from  the  passage  to  which  I  have  already  referred. 
After  dismissing  other  alternatives  which  might  remain  open, 
if  his  own  theory  of  perception  is  rejected,  he  proceeds  as 
follows :  "  Or  we  may  suppose  that  thought  informs  us  of  a 

1  Immediate  knowledge  is  here  contrasted  with  inference.  There  is  a 
fundamental  sense  in  which  all  knowledge,  including  what  is  inferential, 
is  immediate. 


392  G.  F.  STOUT  : 

world  of  things  to  which  our  appearances  are  a  guide.  But 
I  do  not  know  how  that  thought  could  have  experience  of  its 
object  or  what  sort  of  an  object  it  could  be ;  and  indeed  the 
real  world  would  remain  in  this  way  an  unknown."  l  Now, 
when  Mr.  Alexander  speaks  in  this  way,  he  is  using  the  word 
"  experience  "  in  the  narrower  application  as  meaning  im- 
mediate experience  to  the  exclusion  of  any  thought  of  what 
is  not  immediately  experienced.  His  position  is  that  what  is 
not  thus  experienced  cannot  be  known  at  all.  But  this  dis- 
tinction is,  for  him,  only  a  stick  to  beat  a  dog  with.  In 
working  out  his  own  theories,  he  ignores  it  or  denies  it.  For 
him,  the  experience  which  is  identical  with  knowledge  of  a 
sensum,  includes  the  knowledge  of  that  sensum  as  existing 
independently  of  its  appearance  to  us.  But  it  is  only  the 
apparition  as  such  which  can  be  immediately  experienced, 
not  its  existence  independent  of  its  appearance.  Similarly, 
he  takes  for  granted  not  only  that  we  can  experience  the 
same  thing  at  different  moments,  but  that  we  recognise  it  as 
being  the  same  at  the  different  moments.  Again,  he  would 
say  that  our  knowledge  of  other  minds  is  experience.  But 
he  can  hardly  say  that  when  I  know  that  some  one  else  has 
feelings  and  sensations  his  feelings  are  literally  identical  with 
my  feelings  and  that  his  sensing  of  sensa  is  literally  identical 
with  my  sensing  of  sensa.  When,  therefore,  in  the  passage 
quoted,  he  says,  "  I  do  not  know  how  that  thought  which  in- 
forms us  of  a  world  of  things  could  have  experience  of  its 
object,  or  what  sort  of  an  object  it  would  be,"  the  reply  is 
obvious.  In  the  wider  meaning  of  "  experience,"  which 
Alexander  himself  freely  uses,  and  cannot  help  using,  ex- 
perience includes  thought,  which  is  not  experience  in  the 
narrower  sense.  From  this  point  of  view,  the  thought  itself 
is  experience  of  the  object,  and  the  thought  itself  immediately 
reveals  "  what  sort  of  an  object  "  it  is. 

MY  OWN  POSITION. 

I  have  now  attempled  to  state,  in  general,  and  also  to 
criticise,  in  general,  Mr.  Alexander's  account  of  sense  per- 
ception. I  have  yet  to  consider,  in  detail,  the  way  in  which 
he  attempts  to  reconcile  his  fundamental  doctrine  that  the 
sensum  is  simply  identical  with  an  independent  physical 
existence,  with  the  fact,  which  he  like  others  is  bound  to 
recognise,  that  sensa  vary  in  manifold  ways  without  corre- 
sponding variations  in  what  we  take  ourselves  to  see  or  feel 

1  Space,  Time,  and  Deity,  vol.  ii.,  p.  200. 


PROF.   ALEXANDERS   THEORY   OF   SENSE   PERCEPTION.      393 

when  we  experience  them.  But  before  entering  on  this  topic, 
it  will  conduce  to  clearness  if  I  give  a  very  brief  sketch  of  my 
own  view  of  the  way  in  which  we  know  the  material  world. 

First  let  me  say  that  it  seems  to  me  the  most  arbitrary 
dogmatism  for  any  one  to  attempt  to  determine  a  priori  what 
is  and  what  is  not  capable  of  being  known.  If  we  consider 
the  concept  of  knowledge  in  general,  apart  from  the  special 
circumstances  of  this  or  that  individual  knower,  there  is  no 
reason  why  it  should  not  be  coextensive  with  all  being. 
There  is  nothing  to  confine  it  to  this  or  that  part  of  the 
universe,  or  to  anything  short  of  the  whole  in  its  unity  and 
in  its  detail.  That  things  are  known  is  as  much  an  inexplic- 
able fact  as  that  they  exist.  To  ask  how  anything  can  be 
known  is  like  asking  how  anything  can  exist.  Both  are 
wonderful  facts,  but  it  is  no  use  wondering  at  them.  We 
must  take  them  as  we  find  them.  When,  therefore,  we  turn 
to  consider  finite  individuals,  we  must  assume  that  their 
knowledge  is  limited,  not  because  it  is  knowledge,  but  be- 
cause they  are  finite.  The  problem  is  not — '  How  can  I  know 
anything  ? '  but  rather  '  How  is  it  that  I  do  not  know  every- 
thing ? '  What  is  to  be  accounted  for  is  not  knowledge  but 
ignorance  and  error  and  beliefs  that  may  or  may  not  be  true. 

It  is  clear  that  at  least  one  fundamental  reason  of  the 
limitation  of  knowledge  in  finite  individuals  is  the  limitation 
of  their  immediate  experience,  owing  to  its  dependence  on 
what  takes  place  in  their  finite  bodies.  But,  as  I  have  already 
insisted,  if  we  assume  that  what  we  know  is  not  only  limited 
by  immediate  experience  but  primarily  confined  to  im- 
mediate experience,  we  cut  off  all  possibility  of  knowing  any- 
thing beyond  this.  Setting  aside  this  alternative,  what  are 
we  to  substitute  for  it  ?  We  may  find  a  clue  by  taking  into 
account  the  omnipresent  fact  that,  in  a  very  important  sense, 
knowledge  is  not  limited.  It  is  not  possible  to  fix  on  this  or 
that  partial  feature  or  aspect  of  the  universe  and  assert  that 
we  know  this  only,  without,  in  knowing  it,  also  knowing 
something  beyond  it  and  connected  with  it  in  some  sort  of 
unity.  We  cannot,  so  to  speak,  draw  a  chalk  line  circum- 
scribing what  we  know  and  dividing  it  absolutely  from  what 
we  do  not  know.  The  special  items  which  we  regard  as 
known  to  us  always  come  before  us  in  questionable  shape. 
They  are  or  may  be  apprehended  as  essentially  incomplete, 
and  so  raise  questions  concerning  what  is  required  to  com- 
plete them.  And  a  question  always  includes  some  notion  of 
the  general  nature  of  its  answer.  In  wanting  to  know  some- 
thing, we  must  know,  however  indefinitely,  what  it  is  that 
we  want  to  know.  Thus,  what  we  call  ignorance  is  really 


394  G.  F.  STOUT: 

diluted  knowledge.  We  know  what  we  are  ignorant  of  as 
being  unknown  and  as  connected  with  what  we  know. 
There  is  no  reason  why  this  principle  should  not  hold  for 
the  first  beginning  of  our  knowledge  of  the  material  world  as 
well  as  for  its  subsequent  stages;  and  I  therefore  assume 
that  in  primary  sense  knowledge  more  is  immediately  known 
than  is  immediately  experienced.  More  precisely,  I  proceed 
on  the  assumption  that  the  whole  complex  content  of  our 
sense  experience  and  each  of  its  several  discernible  parts  are 
primarily  apprehended  as  continued  into  a  whole  which 
transcends  and  includes  them.1  The  unity  of  the  whole  is 
apprehended  as  a  continuation  of  the  unity  of  that  fragment 
of  it  which  is  immediately  experienced.  Hence  what  is  not 
experienced,  inasmuch  as  it  is  immediately  known  as  being 
of  a  piece  with  what  is  experienced,  must  be  from  the  outset 
apprehended  as  homogeneous  with  it  in  those  general 
respects  without  which  the  continuous  connexion  cannot  be 
thought.  These  will  include  those  fundamental  features  on 
which  the  unity  and  continuity  of  our  own  presentation  con- 
tinuum depends — extension,  temporal  succession  and  change, 
degree  of  intensity,  and,  in  general,  what  Mr.  Alexander 
would  call  categorial  characters. 

For  each  individual  the  material  world  has  two  parts, 
though  it  is  only  in  critical  reflexion  that  he  comes  explicitly 
to  distinguish  them.  There  is,  on  the  one  hand,  his  own 
sensa,  and,  on  the  other,  what  we  may  call  the  physical  ex- 
istence which  is  not  immediately  experienced  by  him  though 
he  has  immediate  knowledge  of  it  in  knowing  his  own  sense 
apparitions.  The  unity  of  his  own  presentation-continuum 
means  for  him  a  corresponding  unity  in  the  physical  world. 
In  knowing  distinctions  and  relations  between  his  own  sensa, 
in  knowing  their  changes  and  variations,  he  knows  corre- 
sponding distinctions  and  relations  in  the  domain  of  physical 
existence. 

This  may  seem  a  large  assumption.  But,  of  itself,  it  will 
not  take  us  far.  It  leaves  us  still  on  the  threshold  of  our 
problem.  Taken  by  itself  it  would  make  the  realm  of 
physical  existence,  as  far  as  we  are  concerned,  merely  an 
idle  duplicate  of  the  content  of  sense  experience.  In  order 
to  account  for  our  knowledge  of  external  objects,  we  have 
still  to  answer  two  questions :  (1)  How  is  it  that  variations 
are  constantly  occurring  in  the  content  of  sense  experience 

1  What  Dr.  Ward  calls  the  '  projection  of  the  self '  seems  to  me  to  be 
equally  primary  and  inseparable  from  this  projection  of  the  presentation 
continuum.  But  for  the  purpose  of  this  paper  I  may  neglect  this  aspect 
of  the  question. 


PEOF.  ALEXANDERS  THEORY  OF  SENSE  PEECEPTION.   395 

which  do  not  imply  corresponding  variations  in  the  external 
objects  which  we  take  ourselves  to  see  or  touch  or  otherwise 
perceive  by  our  senses?  (2)  How  is  it  that  when  these 
variations  are  left  out  of  count  as  irrelevant,  we  can,  none 
the  less,  independently  of  them,  determine  definitely  and 
positively  the  nature  of  the  external  object?  How,  for 
instance,  can  we  determine  the  extent  of  the  thing  seen 
though  we  cannot  identify  this  with  any  one  of  the  variable 
extents  of  the  sense  presentations  which  we  have  in  seeing 
or  touching  it  ? 

The  answer  to  the  first  question  is  found  in  the  distinction 
and  relation  between  the  body  of  the  percipient  and  its  en- 
vironment. We  apprehend  our  own  bodies  in  apprehending 
a  certain  complex  of  sensa  which  we  may  call  the  body-com- 
plex. This  complex  is  persistently  and  continuously  pre- 
sented while  other  sensa  come  and  go.  It  consists,  in  part, 
of  sensa  which  are  the  same  in  kind  and  continuous  in  ex- 
istence with  those  that  we  experience  in  perceiving  other 
physical  existences  and  their  local  and  temporal  distinctions 
and  relations.  Thus,  at  this  moment,  the  visual  presenta- 
tion which  I  have  in  looking  at  my  hand,  forms  part  of  the 
continuous  field  of  visual  experience  which  also  includes  the 
visual  presentation  of  a  table.  The  same  holds  for  touch 
when  I  touch  successively  or  simultaneously  my  hand  and 
the  table.  But  the  body  complex  also  includes  sensa  peculiar 
to  itself  which  enable  each  of  us  to  apprehend  his  own  body 
in  a  way  in  which  we  do  not  apprehend  other  things.  These 
are  (a)  organic  sensa  such  as  hunger,  thirst,  and  what  are 
distinctively  called  bodily  pains  and  pleasures ;  (b)  motor 
sensa,  which  scientific  enquiry  has  found  to  be  conditioned 
by  the  variable  states  of  muscles,  joints  and  tendons,  due  to 
the  variable  position  and  motion  of  the  limbs  and  sense 
organs.  The  first  point  to  be  noted  is  that  the  experiences 
in  which  we  apprehend  the  body  as  visible  and  tangible 
normally  accompany  motor  experiences  and  vary  regularly 
as  these  vary.  The  second  is  that  motor  sensa  are  in  regular 
ways  under  subjective  control.  Apart  from  the  experience 
of  resisted  effort,  we  can  initiate,  continue,  discontinue  or 
change  them  at  will,  or,  at  will,  retain  them  unchanged. 
This  holds  good  independently  of  variable  circumstances. 
I  can  wave  my  hand  whether  I  am  on  the  top  of  Vesuvius 
or  in  my  lecture  room.  Now  this  subjective  control  of 
motor  sensa  also  involves  a  corresponding  control  of  the 
connected  visual  and  tactual  sensa.  This,  however,  is  not 
so  unconditional.  It  depends  on  an  appropriate  adjustment 
of  the  organs  of  sight  and  touch.  I  cannot  see  my  moving 


396  G.  F.  STOUT: 

hand  unless  my  eyes  are  turned  in  the  right  direction.  In 
this  respect  the  perception  of  our  body  and  its  movements 
is  conditioned  like  the  perception  of  objects  external  to  the 
body.  With  this  reservation,  we  may  say  that  control  of 
our  bodily  changes  as  these  are  known  by  way  of  motor 
sensibility  is  also  control  over  the  same  changes  as  known 
by  sight  and  touch. 

I  now  take  a  step  of  vital  importance.  Other  sensa  besides 
those  which  belong  to  the  body-complex  are  also  under  sub- 
jective control.  Their  occurrence  and  cessation,  their  con- 
tinuance and  their  variations  are  constantly  conditioned  by 
perceived  movements  and  positions  of  the  body  which  we  can 
command  at  will.  This  control,  as  compared  with  that 
which  we  have  over  our  own  free  movements,  is  partial, 
limited  and  conditional.  But,  within  its  limits,  it  is  of  a 
regular  and  systematic  character.  It  is  limited,  inasmuch 
as  we  cannot  by  any  motion  of  our  body  or  sense  organs 
determine  ivhat  specific  sense  experiences  we  shall  have. 
We  can  only  determine  their  occurrence,  persistence,  and 
cessation,  and  cause  them  to  change  in  various  regular  ways, 
when  they  are  already  present.  Whenever  I  open  my  eyes  I 
have  certain  visual  presentations,  and  these  regularly  dis- 
appear when  I  close  them.  But  the  opening  of  my  eyes  does 
not,  of  itself,  determine  what  special  presentations  I  shall 
have,  or  how  they  shall  be  grouped.  In  stretching  out  my 
hand  I  get  cutaneous  sensations,  but  whether  these  shall  be 
such  as  arise  in  contact  with  the  air,  with  a  table,  or  with 
water  does  not  depend  on  me.  In  approaching  or  retiring 
from  a  visible  object  the  visual  sensum  which  we  have  in 
perceiving  this  object  increases  and  diminishes  in  magnitude 
in  a  regular  way.  But  which  special  magnitude  it  shall  have 
at  any  given  distance  is  otherwise  determined.  As  a  final 
example,  take  the  experience  of  resisted  effort.  The  degree 
and  character  of  effort  put  forth  is  variable  at  will,  but  the 
degree  and  kind  of  resistance  met  with  is  not.  There  is  thus 
revealed,  in  endlessly  manifold  complex  and  subtle  ways,  the 
antithesis  between  sense  experience  as  dependent  on  the 
motion  and  position  of  the  body,  and  as  dependent  on  things 
external  to  the  body.  Change  and  difference  so  far  as  con- 
ditioned by  our  bodily  position  are  not,  and  are  not  taken  to 
be,  change  and  difference  in  the  external  object  perceived. 
This  is  my  answer  to  the  first  question. 

The  second  question  arises  out  of  this  answer  to  the  first. 
What  is  the  real  nature  of  the  external  object,  if-  we  cannot 
identify  it  with  the  real  nature  of  the  sense  presentations 
which  we  have  in  perceiving  it  ?  Its  character  is  apprehended 


PKOF.  ALEXANDER'S  THEORY  OF  SENSE  PERCEPTION.    397 

as  quite  independent  of  the  bodily  conditions  of  perceiving  it ; 
but  the  sensa  we  have  in  perceiving  it  perpetually  vary  as 
these  conditions  vary.  How  then  can  we  determine  positively 
and  definitely  the  size  and  shape  of  physical  objects  outside 
our  body,  in  distinction  from  the  size  and  shape  of  the 
relevant  visual  and  tactual  sensa?  We  determine  the  in- 
dependent nature  of  objects  external  to  the  sense  organs,  not 
directly  by  their  relation  to  our  sense  experience  but  by 
certain  relations  which  they  have  to  each  other,  relations  of 
such  a  kind  that  they  do  not  vary  with  the  bodily  conditions 
of  perception. 

In  order  to  illustrate  the  general  principle,  it  will  be 
sufficient  to  refer  ojoly  to  causal  relations  and  to  relations  of 
extensive  magnitude.  If  I  turn  on  the  tap  in  my  bath-room, 
water  flows  and  the  bath  begins  to  fill.  Inasmuch  as  the 
flow  of  the  water  is  apprehended  as  causally  conditioned,  in 
the  given  situation,  by  the  turning  of  the  tap,  it  is  a  process 
which  takes  place  independently  of  the  bodily  conditions  of 
perceiving  it.  Even  if  I  leave  the  bath-room  altogether  I 
assume,  that,  because  the  tap  is  turned  on,  the  water  is  still 
flowing  as  it  would  if  I  were  present.  The  characters  of 
external  objects  are  determined  for  us,  in  part,  by  the  differ- 
ences they  make  to  such  independent  causal  processes.  If 
we  look  down  from  a  high  cliff  on  men  on  the  beach  below 
us,  the  visual  apparitions  of  the  men  beneath  us  are  extremely 
small  as  compared  with  those  of  men  standing  beside  us. 
A  child  might  be  led  to  believe  that  the  men  themselves  are 
proportionally  diminutive.  But  from  the  causal  point  of 
view  this  would  mean  that  if  he  were  near  enough,  he  could 
pick  one  of  them  up  and  put  him  in  his  pocket.  Similarly, 
if  an  oar  were  really  bent  in  the  water,  this  would  be  awk- 
ward for  rowers. 

The  extensive  magnitude  of  external  objects  is  in  part 
-determined  by  their  causal  relations.  But  there  is  also  a 
more  direct  way  of  fixing  it,  measurement  by  superposition. 
In  the  first  instance,  the  measurement  is  by  superposition  of 
the  members  of  the  percipient's  own  body  on  each  other  and 
on  external  things. 

This  relation  of  superposition  does  not  itself  fall  within 
immediate  sense  experience.  When  my  hand  is  in  contact 
with  the  table,  there  are  not  two  layers  of  tactual  sensa 
which  cover  each  other.  The  relation  is  between  two 
physical  existences  considered  as  existing  independently  of 
the  bodily  conditions  of  perception  and  the  coming  and  going 
and  other  variations  of  the  sense  impressions  which  are  con- 
nected with  these  bodily  conditions.  So  far  and  so  long  as- 


398  G.  F.  STOUT: 

the  palm  of  my  left  hand  is  in  contact  with  the  table  I  cannot, 
by  any  motor  adjustment,  see  either  the  surface  of  the  table 
or  the  palm  of  my  hand.  I  cannot  touch  either  of  them  with 
the  other  hand,  and  I  can  neither  see  nor  touch  anything 
between  them.  It  is  thus  that  the  relation  of  superposition 
is  revealed  as  independent  of  the  vicissitudes  of  my  sense  ex- 
perience and  its  bodily  conditions.  It  would  be  so  revealed, 
even  if  my  hand  were  insentient,  if,  for  example,  it  were 
made  of  wood.  Nothing  depends  on  the  peculiar  nature  of 
touch  sensations.  They  are  important  only  because,  normally, 
when  we  have  them  our  skin  is  in  contact  with  a  surface  ex- 
ternal to  it.  Hence  they  are  for  us  signs  of  superposition. 
It  is  on  this  condition  that  the  advantage  of  touch  over 
sight  depends.  Otherwise  the  delicacy  of  tactual  discrimi- 
nation of  size  and  shape  is  far  inferior  to  that  of  sight.  It 
is  not  the  superior  precision  of  any  form  of  sense  experi- 
ence which  leads  ultimately  to  the  minute  exactness  of 
scientific  measurement.  It  is  rather  such  relations  as  super- 
position which  do  not  vary  with  the  varying  conditions  of 
sense  experience. 

Such  means  of  assigning  positive  values  to  the  characters 
of  external  objects,  after  discounting  the  conditions  of  per- 
ception, just  because  they  are  founded  on  the  relations  of 
external  objects  to  each  other,  can  yield  only  knowledge  of 
relative  size,  shape  and  position.  Hence  the  modern  doctrine 
of  relativity  is  only  a  complex  development  of  the  relativity 
involved  from  the  outset  in  primitive  stages  of  perceptual 
knowledge.  From  the  same  point  of  view,  we  can  account 
for  the  distinction  of  primary  and  secondary  qualities. 
Secondary  qualities  are  those  which  are  not  thus  determin- 
able  by  the  relations  of  external  objects  to  each  other.  Hence, 
though  we  may  know  them  as  existing  independently  of  the 
variations  of  our  sense  experience,  we  cannot,  or  can  only,  in 
a  very  inadequate  way,  fix  what  they  are  apart  from  these 
variations. 

THE  PRECISE  POINT  AT  ISSUE. 

From  this  account  of  my  own  position,  it  is  clear  wherein 
this  differs  from  that  of  Mr.  Alexander.  We  agree  in 
holding  that  all  knowledge  is  an  immediate  revelation  of 
what  exists.  But  he  maintains  and  I  deny  that  this  im- 
mediate knowledge  is  primarily  confined  to  what  is  im- 
mediately experienced.  This  question  I  have  already  dealt 
with.  But  there  is  another  arising  out  of  his  position 
which  requires  further  discussion.  If  we  start,  as  he 


PEOF.  ALEXANDER'S  THEORY  OF  SENSE  PERCEPTION.    399 

seems  to  suppose,  by  knowing  only  what  we  immediately 
experience,  how  can  we  pass  from  immediately  experienced 
sensa  to  external  objects  ?  According  to  Mr.  Alexander  the 
question  itself  rests  on  a  mistake..  It  rests  on  the  assumption 
that  the  sensuni  is  an  existence  distinct  from  the  external 
object  perceived  in  experiencing  it.  Alexander  on  the  con- 
trary cuts  the  knot  by  assuming  that  when  we  perceive 
something  external  to  the  body  or  sense  organs  the  sensum 
is  simply  identical  with  some  feature  either  of  the  thing  per- 
ceived or  of  some  other  thing  which  we  have  previously 
perceived  or  which  at  any  rate  exists  or  has  existed  in  the 
external  world.  I  have  already  pointed  out  that  even  if  we 
grant  the  identity  as  fact,  this  does  not  explain  how  the 
identity  comes  to  be  known.  This,  however,  is  a  difficulty 
which  does  not  seem  to  trouble  Mr.  Alexander.  But  there 
is  another  which  does  trouble  him,  so  that  he  feels  bound  to 
meet  it  by  an  elaborate  explanation.  He  spends  all  his  in- 
genuity in  attempting  to  answer  the  question  how,  if  the 
sensum  is  always  identical  with  some  feature  of  external 
existence,  it  is  possible  for  the  sensum  to  vary  without  corre- 
sponding variations  in  the  external  object  which  we  perceive 
or  take  ourselves  to  perceive. 

He  uses  the  term  "appearances"  for  sensa  considered 
from  this  point  of  view.  His  general  position  is  that  so  far 
as  appearances  differ  from  what  we  take  ourselves  to  perceive 
this  is  because  in  them  what  really  exists  in  the  external 
world  is  either  only  partially  revealed  or  revealed  in  a  dis- 
torted way. 

EEAL  APPEARANCES. 

Setting  distortions  aside  for  the  moment,  let  us  con- 
sider first  the  fragmentary  nature  of  the  sense  revelation. 
How  is  this  fragmentariness  made  to  account  for  difference 
between  the  sensum  and  the  feature  of  the  external  object 
which  is  supposed  to  be  identical  with  it?  At  first  sight 
it  would  seem  that  there  can  be  no  road  this  way.  For 
if  the  partial  feature  which  is  revealed  is  simply  identical 
with  the  given  sensum,  it  is  hard  to  understand  how  in 
spite  of  this  identity  it  may  yet  differ  from  the  sensum, 
merely  because  there  are  other  partial  features  which  are  not 
revealed.  It  would  seem  that  to  account  for  this  there  must 
be  distortion  as  well  as  deficiency.  In  fact,  as  we  shall  see, 
Mr.  Alexander  does  everywhere  introduce  distortion,  without 
recognising  that  he  is  doing  so.  Appearances  supposed  to 
be  partial  but  not  distorted  are  called  by  Alexander  real 


400  G.  F.  STOUT: 

appearances.  A  simple  example  is  the  change  in  the  bright- 
ness of  a  light,  or  the  loudness  of  a  sound,  as  we  approach 
the  source  or  recede  from  it.  According  to  Alexander  "  the 
mind  situated  further  off  selects  a  portion  of  the  thing  ". 
Part  of  this  is  identical  with  the  sensum,  other  parts  are  not 
This  would  seem  a  simple  and  straightforward  explanation, 
if  we  could  attach  a  satisfactory  meaning  to  the  phrase  "  part 
of  the  brightness ".  But  according  to  Alexander  himself 
there  are  no  such  parts.  As  he  immediately  goes  on  to  say, 
the  "  selection  of  the  lower  brightness  from  the  real  bright- 
ness does  not  mean  that  that  real  brightness  is  divisible  into 
parts,  as  if  intensities  could  be  obtained  by  addition  ".  This 
being  so,  I,  at  any  rate,  see  no  way  of  avoiding  the  conclu- 
sion that,  inasmuch  as  there  are  no  parts  to  select  from,  no 
parts  can  be  selected.  Each  degree  of  brightness  as  im- 
mediately experienced  is  a  distinct  degree,  occupying  its  own 
place  in  the  intensive  scale.  To  say  that  the  real  brightness 
contains  the  others  is  merely  a  very  inaccurate  way  of  saying 
that  it  is  more  intense  or,  at  any  rate,  not  less  intense  than 
any  of  them.  It  is  therefore  not  surprising  that  side  by  side 
with  this,  Mr.  Alexander  gives  another  and  quite  different 
explanation  of  what  it  is  that  is  selected  from  the  total  ob- 
ject. This  is  now  said  to  be  not  part  of  the  intensive  quality, 
but  part  of  the  external  stimulus  which  conditions  the  ap- 
prehension of  it.  On  this  view,  "  the  distance  from  a  sound 
selects  that  amplitude  of  the  qualitative  vibration  which 
represents  the  diminished  intensity  produced  by  distance ". 
The  difficulty  here  is  that  no  such  selection  takes  place,  and 
also  that  if  it  did  it  would  not  be  what  is  required.  Selection, 
in  the  only  relevant  sense,  means  that  part  of  the  external 
object  is  a  sensum  and  part  not.  But  in  seeing  brightness  or 
hearing  sounds  the  light  and  sound  vibrations  are  not  pre- 
sented as  sensa  either  wholly  or  fractionally;  and  even  if 
they  were  they  would  not  be  identical  with  the  brightness  or 
the  sound.  They  would  not  be  so  either  in  fact  or  according 
to  Mr.  Alexander.  For,  according  to  him,  a  sensible  quality 
is  something  new  which  emerges  when  certain  motions  occur. 
It  is  not  identical  with  the  motions  themselves.  Thus  the 
alleged  selection  from  the  amplitude  of  the  vibration  merely 
means  that  the  occurrence  and  nature  of  the  sensum  depends 
not  directly  on  the  vibration  as  it  initially  proceeds  from  the 
external  object,  but  on  the  way  in  which  the  previous  state 
of  the  sense  organ  and  nervous  system  is  modified  by  that 
phase  of  the  vibration  which  reaches  the  ear.  Wherever  the 
vibration  comes  from  and  however  it  may  originally  be  set 
going,  the  sound  sensum  is  determined  by  that  phase  of  it  in 


PEOF.  ALEXANDER'S  THEORY  OF  SENSE  PERCEPTION.    401 

which  it  arrives  at  the  sense  organ  and  contributes  to  deter- 
mine changes  in  this  and  in  connected  neural  arrangements. 
In  other  words  the  occurrence  and  nature  of  the  sensum  de- 
pends directly  only  on  what  takes  place  in  the  body  of  the 
percipient,  however  this  may  be  occasioned.  But  this  is  just 
what  Alexander  is  concerned  to  deny. 

Let  us,  however,  suppose  that,  in  some  relevant  sense, 
part  of  an  intensity  may  be  revealed  in  sense  experience  and 
part  not.  Such  partial  presentation  will  not  cover  the  facts 
unless  it  is  taken  also  to  involve  distortion. 

What  is  revealed  as  a  sensum,  so  far  as  it  is  thus  revealed, 
is  itself  a  distinct  and  separate  intensity,  not  part  of  an 
intensity.  The  part  in  being  cut  off  from  the  whole  to 
which  it  is  supposed  to  belong,  becomes  itself  a  distinct 
intensive  whole,  a  distinct  degree  of  intensity  occupying  its 
own  place  in  the  intensive  scale.  Thus  a  less  intensive 
magnitude  is  substituted  for  the  intensive  magnitude  of  the 
external  and  distinct  sound  or  brightness.  This  is  distortion. 
But  Mr.  Alexander  cannot  admit  distortion  in  what  he  calls 
"real  appearances".  The  real  appearances  are  the  basis 
and  presupposition  of  all  others  and  they  are  called  real  just 
because  they  are  assumed  not  to  be  distorted  by  bodily  or 
mental  conditions. 

So  far  I  have  been  considering  only  whether  Mr.  Alexander's 
theory  is  tenable,  when  examined  from  the  point  of  view  of 
our  present  knowledge  of  the  external  world  and  of  the 
conditions  of  perceiving  it.  But  there  is  a  further  question 
which,  though  it  is  altogether  of  vital  importance  to  his 
general  position,  is  completely  ignored  by  him.  Let  us 
grant  that  the  several  degrees  of  brightness  which  we  im- 
mediately experience  in  approaching  a  source  of  light  form 
an  ascending  scale  which  has  its  upper  limit  in  the  bright- 
ness of  the  external  obtect  and  that  this  brightness  exists 
quite  independently  of  our  sense  experience  and  its  bodily 
conditions.  Let  us  grant  that  this  holds  good  in  such  a  way 
that,  at  least  metaphorically,  we  may  legitimately  speak  of 
the  several  degrees  of  brightness  as  parts  of  the  external 
brightness.  Conceding  all  this,  we  have  still  to  inquire 
whether  it  is  included  in  the  primary  sense  knowledge  of 
the  percipient.  Is  the  knowledge  a  constituent  condition  of 
the  first  apprehension  of  the  external  object  as  such  ?  If 
Mr.  Alexander  had  faced  this  question,  he  would,  I  submit, 
have  found  himself  caught  between  the  horns  of  a  very 
serious  dilemma.  If  he  says  "yes"  then  he  must  frankly 
and  consistently  surrender  the  assumption  that  we  can 
primarily  know  only  what  we  immediately  experience  as  we 

26 


402  G.  F.  STOUT: 

experience  a  present  sensum.  What  thus  enters  experience 
is  only  a  part  of  the  external  intensity.  If  it  not  only  is 
a  part,  but  is  apprehended  as  being  a  part,  there  is  the 
knowledge  of  an  intensive  whole,  which  includes  it,  and  this 
whole,  ex  hypothesi,  is  not  itself  a  sensum,  and  has  never 
been  a  sensum,  or  if  it  has  it  cannot  be  known  to  have  been 
a  sensum.  I  should  say  that  the  intensive  whole,  if  it  is. 
primarily  known,  is  known  by  a  thought  which  has  its 
source  in  the  essential  incompleteness  of  immediate  ex- 
perience. In  the  strict  use  of  language,  I  prefer  to  say  that 
it  is  known  by  experience  rather  than  that  it  is  itself  experi- 
enced. Mr.  Alexander,  on  the  contrary,  may  insist  if  he 
likes  in  calling  thought,  as  such,  a  kind  of  experience.  The 
question  concerns  only  the  employment  of  words,  and  does 
not  touch  the  real  issue.  The  essential  point  is  that  on  any 
view  the  bare  immediacy  of  sense  is  transcended,  and  so 
transcended  as  to  yield  knowledge  of  what  Hume  called 
matter  of  fact  in  distinction  from  relation  of  ideas.  More  is 
immediately  known  than  is  immediately  experienced. 

On  the  other  hand,  if  it  is  said  that  the  partial  intensities 
are  not  primarily  apprehended  as  partial,  Mr.  Alexander 
seems  to  be  impaled  on  another  horn  of  the  dilemma.  How 
do  the  parts  of  the  whole  external  intensity  come  to  be  appre- 
hended as  being  parts  of  it  ?  Or,  what  comes  to  the  same 
thing,  how  is  the  existence  of  the  whole  external  intensity 
known  at  all  ?  It  must  be  remembered  that  for  Mr.  Alexander 
the  apprehension  of  real  appearances  is  the  basis  of  all 
further  knowledge  of  the  external  world.  It  is  here,  there- 
fore, if  anywhere,  that  we  must  look  for  the  answer  to  our 
question.  But  he  fails  to  supply  any  answer,  and  none  can 
be  given  consistent  with  the  assumption  that  we  primarily 
know  only  what  we  immediately  experience.  He  is  thus, 
after  all  his  pains  and  ingenuity,  faced  with  what  is,  in 
principle,  the  old  insoluble  problem.  If  we  begin  by  knowing 
only  our  own  sensa,  how  can  we  ever  get  beyond  them? 
The  difficulty  is  not  met  and  is  hardly  mitigated  by  saying 
that  the  sensa  are  in  fact  identical  with  partial  features  of 
the  external  object. 

Keal  appearances  vary  not  only  in  intensity  but  in  size 
and  shape.  When  we  move  away  from  a  plate  at  right 
angles  to  its  centre,  the  relevant  visual  sensum  retains  its 
shape,  but  diminishes  in  size  as  the  retinal  surface  excited 
becomes  smaller.  Yet  the  size  of  the  external  object  as 
determined  by  measurement  and  the  part  it  plays  in  causal 
process  remains  constant.  If  the^  plate  is  seen  obliquely  the 
shrinking  is  greater  for  one  axis  than  another  and  its  sensible 
shape  varies  in  consequence.  The  sensum  is  elliptical  in- 


PEOF.  ALEXANDER'S  THEORY  OF  SENSE  PERCEPTION.    403 

stead  of  circular.  According  to  Mr.  Alexander,  "  the  dis- 
tance of  the  eye  from  the  plate  acts  selectively  as  with  the 
varying  degrees  of  brightness ;  the  size  which  we  see  is  a 
portion  of  the  real  geometrical  size  of  the  plate  ".1  Here  he 
tacitly  assumes  that  what  we  see  is  identical  with  the  visual 
sensum  which  we  have  in  seeing.  This  is  contrary  to  the 
ordinary  use  of  language,  and  gives  rise  to  great  confusion. 
What  we  take  ourselves  to  see  is  not  merely  the  size  of  the 
visual  sensum  but  the  size  of  the  external  object  as  sug- 
gested under  the  given  conditions  by  the  visual  sensum.  As 
I  approach  or  retire  from  the  plate  there  are  certain  limits 
of  distance  within  which  I  do  not  ordinarily  notice  the  differ- 
ence between  the  successive  visual  experiences  so  as  to  com- 
pare them.  I  have  learned  to  regard  them  as  due  merely 
to  bodily  conditions  of  perception  and  therefore  as  irrele- 
vant. Hence  I  see  the  plate  as  of  the  same  constant  size  and 
shape  in  spite  of  them.  Beyond  these  limits  of  distance  I 
become  aware  of  the  sensible  variations  as  such,  and  then 
they  perceptually  suggest  corresponding,  though  not  propor- 
tionate, variations  in  the  external  size  and  shape.  So  far  as 
this  happens,  I  still  take  myself  to  see  the  size  and  shape  of 
the  external  objects.  The  only  difference  is  that  I  may  re- 
cognise that  I  see  them  inaccurately.  Mr.  Alexander,  in 
identifying  the  sensation  with  what  is  seen,  shares  the 
fundamental  fallacy  of  Berkeley  that  we  properly  and 
primarily  perceive  only  what  we  immediately  experience. 

External  size  and  shape  is  of  course  the  same  whether  we 
are  conversant  with  it  by  way  of  sight  or  by  way  of  touch, 
so  far  as  the  perception  is  not  mistaken.  But  this  does  not 
imply  that  the  extensive  tactual  sensum  is  ever  identical 
with  the  extension  of  visual  sensa.  This  identity  is  asserted 
by  Mr.  Alexander ;  but  he  does  not  even  attempt  to  meet  the 
cogent  argument  against  it  in  Berkeley's  Theory  of  Vision. 
He  merely  appeals  to  a  simple  experiment.  "  We  have  only 
to  hold  the  plate  in  our  hands  and  move  it  away  ...  in 
order  to  assure  ourselves  that  the  touch  and  the  colour  of 
the  plate  are  in  the  same  place."  Now  I  agree  that  this 
experience  yields  evidence  of  the  identity  of  extension  as 
seen,  and  extension  as  touched.  But  it  does  not  in  the  least 
show  that  visual  and  tactual  sensa  are  included  within  the 
same  continuous  extension.  What  is  really  relevant  and 
important  is  that  the  extent  of  the  plate  as  measured  by 
superposition  of  the  hand  remains  constant,  while  the  visual 
sensa  vary.  The  constancy  of  tactual  sensa  as  compared 

1  Space,  Time,  and  Deity,  vol.  ii.,  p.  194. 


404  G.  F.  STOUT: 

with  visual  is  not  a  superiority  but  a  defect.  It  is  to  be 
noted  that  they  are  not  constant  except  for  the  same  part  of 
the  skin ;  and  even  with  this  restriction  the  constancy  is 
only  due  to  the  fact  that  the  conditions  under  which  the 
tactual  experience  is  gained  are  strictly  fixed  and  limited 
instead  of  being  widely  variable  as  they  are  for  sight.  But 
this  is  merely  a  defect  to  be  added  to  the  other  imperfections 
of  touch  as  compared  with  vision.  The  tactual  sensum  is 
constant  only  in  the  way  in  which  any  one  of  the  alternative 
visual  presentations  is  constant  so  long  as  the  eyes  are  turned 
in  the  same  direction,  and  the  thing  seen  is  at  the  same  dis- 
tance. The  difference  is  that  tactual  experience  is  limited  to 
one  set  of  conditions  and  does  not  occur  at  all  without  them. 

It  follows  from  what  I  have  just  said  that  neither  the  real 
nor  the  apparent  shape  of  the  external  object  is  identical 
with  the  size  or  shape  of  the  visual  apparition  immediately 
experienced.  The  real  shape  and  size  of  the  external  object 
is  determinable  by  measurement  and  causal  relations.  Its 
apparent  size  and  shape  is  what  we,  rightly  or  wrongly, 
estimate  the  real  size  and  shape  to  be  as  suggested  by 
present  sense  experience  in  conjunction  with  preacquired 
knowledge.  This  being  so,  there  is  no  d  priori  reason  for 
accepting  Mr.  Alexander's  position  that  the  size  of  the 
sensum  and  the  external  size  differ  only  as  part  and  whole, 
the  extent  of  the  sensum  being  only  a  portion  of  the  extent 
of  the  thing  seen.  We  have  now  to  consider  whether  this 
hypothesis  fits  the  facts  better  or  worse  than  the  alternative 
view  that  the  sensum  depends  directly  and  ultimately  only 
on  the  way  in  which  the  sense  organ  is  affected. 

Extensive  magnitude  unlike  intensive  does  contain  distinct 
parts  and  we  may  therefore  speak  quite  literally  of  some 
parts  being  revealed  in  sense  experience  while  others  are  un- 
revealed.  But  this  is  not  an  accurate  description  of  what  we 
observe  when  a  visual  presentation  shrinks  as  the  distance 
from  the  thing  seen  increases.  It  is  not  correct  to  say  that 
some  parts  vanish  while  others  persist.  Each  discernible 
part  shrinks  as  well  as  the  whole  and  the  whole  shrinks  only 
because  the  parts  shrink.  Details  do  disappear  but  only  be- 
cause they  gradually  become  too  small  to  be  distinguishable, 
until  at  the  last  we  are  left  with  a  blur  in  which  none  of  the 
original  details  can  be  discerned.  This  does  not  fit  in  well 
with  Mr.  Alexander's  theory.  But  it  is  just  what  we  should 
expect  if  the  visual  magnitude  is  correlated  with  retinal  and 
nervous  process  and  is  dependent  on  other  factors  only  if  and 
so  far  as  they  condition  this. 

Even  if,  setting  aside   this   difficulty,  we   suppose  that 


PROF.  ALEXANDER'S  THEORY  OF  SENSE  PERCEPTION.     405 

what  happens  is  that  some  parts  are  taken  and  others  left, 
this  is  not  enough.  It  does  not  explain  how  or  why  the 
selected  parts  close  with  each  other  and  run  together  in  one 
continuous  immediately  experienced  extension,  instead  of 
having  distances  or  gaps  between  them,  corresponding  to  the 
parts  selected.  This  involves  more  than  mere  selection.  It 
is  also  distortion  of  the  kind  which  Mr.  Alexander  would 
class  as  illusion.  Parts  which  are  immediately  contiguous 
in  sense  experience  are  separated  by  intervals  in  the  external 
object.  In  Mr.  Alexander's  language,  they  are  seen  in  situa- 
tions which  do  not  really  belong  to  them.  We  thus  again 
reach  the  result  that  the  real  appearance  in  which  the  exter- 
nal object  is  supposed  to  be  simply  identical  with  the  sensum 
is,  in  fact,  infected  through  and  through  with  illusive  dis- 
tortion. But  the  basis  of  Mr.  Alexander's  theory  is  that  real 
appearance  is  free  from  illusion.  It  is  indeed  for  that  reason 
that  he  calls  it  real.  There  is  also  the  further  difficulty  that 
the  distortion  as  distinguished  from  mere  selection  requires 
a  separate  special  explanation  on  another  principle.  I  do 
not  doubt  that  Mr.  Alexander's  ingenuity  could  devise  one. 
But  it  is  the  extreme  of  perversity  to  put  forward  two  radi- 
cally distinct  hypotheses,  both  of  a  very  complicated  nature, 
when  the  facts  themselves  carry  one  simple,  obvious  and 
adequate  explanation,  so  to  speak,  written  on  their  face. 
The  size  and  shape  of  the  sensum  varies  directly  with  the 
retinal  excitation  whatever  factor  may  be  concerned  in  pro- 
ducing this. 

Before  leaving  the  subject  of  real  appearance,  I  may  note 
that  the  same  epistemological  difficulty  confronts  Mr.  Alex- 
ander for  extensive  as  for  intensive  variations.  Does  the 
percipient  subject  himself  know  in  primary  sense  knowledge 
that  there  is  a  total  extension  containing  all  the  parts  re- 
vealed to  him  as  sensa  ?  Does  he  primarily  apprehend  the 
parts  as  parts  of  this  whole  ?  If  he  does,  then  primary  sense 
knowledge  transcends  immediate  experience.  On  the  other 
hand  if  parts  are  not  apprehended  as  parts,  how  can  we  ever 
come  to  know  that  there  is  a  whole  which  transcends  and 
includes  them  ? 

MERE  APPEARANCES. 

According  to  Alexander  the  distinctive  character  of  the 
appearances  which  he  calls  real  is  that  though  they  are 
selected  from  the  whole  nature  of  the  thing  perceived 
they  are  not  otherwise  altered.  Besides  this  he  recognises 
two  other  kinds  of  appearances  which  are  not  merely 


406  G.  F.  STOUT: 

selected  but  distorted.  The  word  "  distorted  "  means  that 
instead  of  the  external  object  which  we  take  ourselves  to 
perceive,  something  else  is  substituted  more  or  less  different 
from  it.  Strictly  following  out  his  general  philosophy  of 
perception,  Mr.  Alexander  maintains  that  what  is  thus  sub- 
stituted does  not  at  all  owe  its  nature  and  existence  to  any 
process  occurring  in  the  body  of  the  percipient ;  on  the  con- 
trary it  is  always  some  feature  or  other  in  the  external  world, 
existing  quite  independently  of  the  occurrence  of  sensations 
and  their  bodily  conditions.  There  is  distortion  only  inas- 
much as  this  independent  existence  is  sensuously  revealed  in 
connexion  with  a  thing  to  which  it  does  not  belong  :  and  this 
means  that  it  is  revealed  in  a  place  where  it  really  is  not  or 
at  a  time  when  it  really  is  not.  Such  misleading  revelations 
are  traced  to  different  sources.  They  may  be  due  to  the  mind 
of  the  percipient,  which  includes  for  Alexander  the  bodily 
conditions  of  perception.  When  this  occurs  the  appearances 
are  called  illusory.  On  the  other  hand  the  distortion  may  be 
due  merely  to  the  combination  of  the  thing  perceived  with 
other  things  which  are  also  themselves  perceived  or  at  least 
capable  of  being  so.  The  sense- appearance  is  then  called  a 
mere  appearance.  It  is  with  mere  appearances  that  we  are 
at  present  concerned. 

At  the  outset,  I  find  it  impossible  to  obtain  from  Mr. 
Alexander  any  consistent  and  intelligible  account  of  what  a 
mere  appearance  is.  On  two  points,  indeed,  he  is  clear. 
The  mere  appearance  is  not  identical  with  any  feature  of  the 
external  object  to  which  it  is  referred  by  the  percipient,  when 
this  is  considered  in  detachment  from  its  environment.  The 
partially  immersed  stick,  when  considered  by  itself,  apart 
from  its  immersion,  is  not  bent  as  it  seems  to  be.  In  the 
second  place,  the  mere  appearance  is  in  some  way  identical 
with  a  feature  of  the  total  situation  composed  of  the  special 
object  perceived  and  other  objects  combined  with  this.  It  is 
when  we  inquire  how  this  can  be  that  the  puzzle  begins. 
I  find  in  Mr.  Alexander  two  distinct  accounts  of  what  takes 
place ;  and  neither  of  them  seems  tenable.  Both  are  given 
side  by  side  in  the  following  passage.  In  mere  appearance, 
"  we  do  not  sense  the  thing  of  which  we  apprehend  the  mere 
appearance  taken  by  itself,  but  in  connexion  with  some  other 
thing  which  modifies  it  "-1  Let  me  here  interrupt  the 
quotation  to  say  that  this  is  the  first  alternative.  What  is 
relevant  in  the  sensum  is,  on  this  view,  really  a  feature  of 
the  particular  external  object  perceived,  as  this  object  is  really 

1  Space,  Time,  and  Deity,  vol.  ii.,  p.  191. 


PEOF.  ALEXANDER'S  THEORY  OF  SENSE  PERCEPTION.    407 

modified  by  something  else.  In  the  rest  of  the  quotation 
Mr.  Alexander  drops  this  view  and  passes,  without  being 
aware  of  the  discrepancy,  to  a  quite  different  position. 
"  What  we  sense  or  otherwise  apprehend  is  not  the  thing  by 
itself,  but  a  new  thing  of  which  the  thing  forms  a  part ;  and 
there  is  no  reason  to  suppose,  illusion  barred,  the  compound 
thing  does  not  really  possess  what  we  sense."  Here  the 
sensum  is  identified,  not  with  a  feature  of  the  perceived  thing 
as  this  is  modified  by  its  environing  conditions,  but  with  a 
feature  of  a  compound  object  conditioned  by  the  combination 
of  the  thing  perceived  with  other  things. 

Both  these  explanations  break  down  hopelessly :  and  Mr. 
Alexander  is  only  able  to  conceal  the  inadequacy  of  each  of 
them  by  oscillating  between  it  and  the  other.  Take  first  the 
modification  theory.  If  the  perceived  object  is  really  modified 
by  the  conditions  under  which  it  exists,  this  means  that  it 
really  has  a  character  which  would  not  characterise  it  if 
these  were  absent.  It  is  this  character  which  is  revealed  in 
the  mere  appearance.  What  is  revealed  as  a  sensum  does  in 
fact  belong  to  that  external  object  which  we  take  ourselves 
to  perceive.  It  is  plain  that  if  this  were  so,  there  would  be 
no  distinction  between  a  mere  appearance  and  a  real  appear- 
ance. As  a  matter  of  fact,  what  Mr.  Alexander  calls  mere 
appearances  are  not  constituted  in  this  way.  The  water  does 
not  really  bend  the  stick  in  which  it  is  plunged.  What  is 
modified  in  both  instances  is  the  light  in  its  passage  to  the 
eye,  and  the  retinal  excitation,  and  the  visual  presentation 
dependent  on  this.  We  are  no  better  off  if  we  try  the  other 
alternative,  that  what  is  revealed  as  a  sensum  is  a  character 
of  a  composite  external  object  containing,  as  a  part  of  itself, 
the  particular  thing  which  we  perceive.  It  is  not  true  that 
the  bend  in  the  visual  presentation  when  we  see  a  partially 
immersed  oar,  is  identical  with  a  bend  of  the  whole  physical 
complex  constituted  by  the  water  and  the  oar.  There  is  no 
such  bend  ;  what  is  true  is  that  this  complex  of  external  con- 
ditions gives  rise  to  refraction  of  the  light  proceeding  to  the 
eye,  and  thereby  determines  the  retinal  process  in  such  a  way 
that  the  visual  sensum  is  really  bent.  Similarly  when  we 
see  a  distant  mountain  through  a  haze,  it  is  not  true  that  the 
colour-quality  which  we  immediately  experience  is  really 
spread  over  the  surface  both  of  the  haze  and  mountain.  In 
what  way  then  can  it  be  said  to  belong  to  both  of  them  to- 
gether if  it  belongs  to  neither  of  them  separately  ?  To  say 
that  it  belongs  to  both  together  is  only  a  very  inaccurate  way 
of  stating  the  obvious  fact.  The  light  reflected  from  the 
mountain  is  so  altered  by  its  passage  through  the  haze  as  to 


408  G.  F.  STOUT: 

affect  the  eye  as  it  would  not  otherwise  do  and  so  gives  rise 
to  different  visual  presentations. 

We  have  yet  to  consider  a  third  formula  used  by  Mr. 
Alexander,  which  is  inconsistent  with  either  of  the  others. 
The  sensum  is  supposed  to  be  identical  with  some  feature  of 
an  object  existing  in  the  environment  of  the  percipient :  but 
owing  to  other  conditions  also  existing  in  the  environment, 
what  is  thus  revealed  as  a  sensum  is  revealed  in  a  place  in 
which  it  is  not  really  present.  How  far  this  explanation  is 
supposed  to  cover  mere  appearances  in  general,  I  am  not 
sure.  It  is  applied  by  Mr.  Alexander  especially  to  one  mere 
appearance,  reflexion  in  a  plain  mirror,  assumed  to  be  flaw- 
less. Let  us  suppose  that  what  is  reflected  is  the  body  of  a 
man  facing  the  glass.  Then,  according  to  Mr.  Alexander, 
the  shape,  size  and  colouring  of  the  man  is  really  where  the 
man  is,  some  distance  in  front  of  the  mirror.  But  for  one 
who  sees  the  reflexion  this  identical  shape,  size  and  colour 
is  immediately  experienced  in  a  place  where  it  is  not,  i.e., 
some  distance  behind  the  surface  of  the  glass. 

This  theory,  if  it  is  taken  strictly,  I  hold  to  be  quite  im- 
possible. But  it  is  important  that  it  should  be  taken  strictly, 
and  not  confused  with  $nother  position  which  no  one,  I  pre- 
sume, would  dispute.  Undoubtedly  when  we  see  a  man  re- 
flected in  a  mirror,  his  shape  and  size,  and  consequently  the 
man  himself  appear,  i.e.,  seem  to  be  where  they  really  are  not, 
or  seem  as  if  they  were  where  they  really  are  not.  If  the 
percipient  does  not  otherwise  know  the  contrary,  he  will  be- 
lieve that  there  is  a  man  behind  the  mirror.  A  baby,  for 
instance,  may  feel  for  the  man  whom  he  takes  to  be  in  front 
of  him.  To  the  baby  it  seems  that  there  is  a  man  there.  To 
us  it  only  seems  as  if  there  were  a  man  there. 

Up  to  this  point  the  word  "  appears  "  has  been  used  as  a 
synonym  of  "seems".  I  have  not  spoken  of  appearing  ab- 
solutely, but  only  of  something  appearing  or  seeming  to  be 
this  or  that,  or  appearing  as  if  it  were  this  or  that.  But  the 
word  appearing  has  also  another  and  a  radically  different 
meaning.  It  may  be  used  absolutely.  Now  if  and  so  far  as 
anything  really  appears  in  this  sense  it  really  is  as  it  appears. 
If  the  man  himself  really  appears  behind  the  mirror  he  really 
is  behind  the  mirror.  The  apparition  is  the  reality  itself  ap- 
pearing. There  is  no  question  of  seeming.  Whoever  may 
deny  this,  Mr.  Alexander  cannot  consistently  do  so.  For  his 
whole  philosophy  of  perception  is  based  on  the  assumption 
that  what  is  revealed  in  immediate  sense  experience  exists  as 
a  feature  of  the  external  world.  This  presupposes  that  at 
least  it  really  exists. 


PROF.  ALEXANDER'S  THEORY  OF  SENSE  PERCEPTION.    409 

The  relevant  visual  sensum  which  we  have  on  looking  at 
the  reflexion  of  a  man  in  a  mirror  does  really  appear  and 
not  merely  seem  to  be  in  a  certain  place  with  a  certain  situa- 
tion relatively  to  other  places.  This  is  possible  inasmuch  as 
it  is  a  locally  distinct  part  of  the  total  field  of  visual  sensa 
experienced  at  the  time.  It  is  a  sense  apparition  revealed 
within  a  more  extensive  apparition  which  is  itself  revealed 
in  the  same  way.  Within  this  continuous  whole  it  is  im- 
mediately experienced  in  certain  local  relations  to  other  sensa, 
e.g.,  those  which  we  have  in  seeing  the  frame  of  the  mirror 
or  articles  on  our  dressing  table.  An  appeal  to  immediate 
experience  yields  unambiguous  evidence  that  it  does  really 
appear  and  does  therefore  exist  in  these  relations  and  does 
not  merely  seem  to  be  in  them.  Unfortunately  for  Mr. 
Alexander,  this  appeal  to  immediate  experience  makes 
nonsense  of  his  whole  doctrine  of  sense  knowledge.  It  makes 
nonsense  of  his  fundamental  doctrine  that  sensa  are  identical 
with  characters  of  the  external  object.  For  the  form  and 
colour  of  the  man  whose  reflexion  we  see  is  not  really  placed 
relatively  to  the  frame  of  the  looking  glass,  as  the  correspond- 
ing visual  apparitions  are  really  placed  in  relation  to  each 
other.  If  the  form  and  colour  of  the  man  are  identical  with 
the  form  and  colour  immediately  experienced,  when  his  re- 
flexion is  seen,  then  the  form  and  colour  of  the  man  must 
really  exist,  and  not  merely  appear  to  exist,  in  two  separate 
places  at  the  same  time.  This  is  most  clearly  shown  by  a 
fact  which  evidently  puzzles  Mr.  Alexander,  as  it  ought  to 
do.  "If  "  he  says,  "  you  touch  a  thing  like  a  pencil  which  is 
in  front  of  you  so  that  you  see  it  directly  and  also  in  the 
mirror,  the  judgment  is  troubled.  For  the  virtual  image  is 
only  seen  with  the  help  of  the  mirror,  and  the  real  pencil  is 
seen  as  well  as  touched  ;  and  there  are  thus  two  visions  of 
space  at  once."  l  On  my  view  this  means  that  though  we 
see  the  same  single  external  object,  there  really  are  three 
distinct  sensa,  two  visual  and  one  tactual.  But  if,  like 
Alexander,  we  identify  the  single  external  object  with  the 
several  sensa  we  are  in  a  desperate  position.  The  visual 
apparitions  are  really  distinct  within  the  field  of  visual  ex- 
perience, and  separated  from  each  other  by  an  experienced 
interval.  Immediate  experience  reveals  their  local  separation 
just  as  it  reveals  their  shape  and  colour.  I  have  as  little 
right  to  deny  that  there  are  two  of  them  as  to  deny  that  they 
exist  at  all.  It  is  just  because  there  are  two  visual  sensa  that 
it  seems  as  if  there  were  two  external  objects — two  hands. 

1  Space,  Time,  and  Deity,  vol.  ii.,  p.  198. 


410  G.   F.    STOUT  : 

It  is  strongly,  vividly  and  insistently  suggested  that  there  are 
two  hands,  only  because  in  ordinary  vision  there  are  usually 
two  external  objects  where  two  visual  presentations  are  dis- 
tinguished. It  is  futile  to  urge  that  the  same  sensum  is  twice 
apprehended  and  on  this  account  seems  itself  to  be  doubled. 
For  there  is  no  way  of  distinguishing  the  awareness  of  one 
sensum  from  that  of  the  other  except  by  distinguishing  the 
sensa  themselves. 

ILLUSOKY  APPEARANCES. 

Illusory  and  mere  appearances  are,  for  Mr.  Alexander,, 
essentially  akin  inasmuch  as  in  both  of  them  a  sensum 
appears  in  connexion  with  an  external  object  to  which 
it  does  not  really  belong.  But  there  is  a  difference  in  the 
conditions  under  which  this  takes  place.  In  mere  appear- 
ance the  displacement  is  due  to  factors  external  to  the  body 
of  the  percipient.  An  illusion,  on  the  contrary,  is  due 
to  what  occurs  within  the  sensitive  organism.  Both  in 
illusion  and  mere  appearance,  what  is  sensibly  revealed  dis- 
agrees with  what  really  exists  only  so  far  as  a  sensum  is  mis- 
placed in  space  or  time.  The  sensum  itself  which  is  thus 
misplaced  is  supposed  to  be  identical  with  something  which 
really  exists  in  the  external  world  at  some  place  or  time.  In 
mere  appearance,  it  is  supposed  to  be  somehow  contained  in 
the  total  situation  which  confronts  the  percipient.  In 
illusion  it  may  be  anywhere. 

I  have  already  examined  the  conception  of  something  as 
appearing  in  a  place  in  which  it  is  not.  The  same  difficulty 
which  I  have  noted  in  dealing  with  the  mirror,  arises  here 
also.  ''There  is,"  says  Alexander,  "no  illusion  until  an 
element  in  the  appearance  which  does  not  belong  to  the 
thing  is  perceived  as  belonging  to  it :  until,  for  instance,  the 
green  seen  by  contrast  on  a  piece  of  grey  paper  lying  on  a 
red  ground  is  seen  as  an  affection  of  the  place  of  the  grey 
paper.  The  green  by  itself  is  not  illusory,  but  the  patch, 
occupied  by  the  grey,  seen  as  green."  (II.,  p.  209.)  I 
would  here  first  inquire  what  ground  we  have  for  asserting 
the  existence  of  the  green  sensum.  The  only  answer  and 
the  sufficient  answer  is  that  the  green  is  actually  revealed 
within  immediate  sense  experience.  But  on  the  same 
principle  we  are  also  bound  to  assert  that  the  green  sensum 
does  not  merely  seem  to  be  actually  placed  within  the  red. 
For  what  is  immediately  experienced  is  a  green  situated 
within  a  red  field  and  continuous  with  it.  This  green  there- 
fore does  not  merely  seem,  but  actually  is,  within  the  red. 


PROF.  ALEXANDER'S  THEORY  OF  SENSE  PERCEPTION.    411 

But,  according  to  Alexander,  the  red  as  sensed  is  identical 
with  the  red  colour  of  the  paper,  and  the  colour  of  the  paper 
is  where  the  paper  is  and  nowhere  else.  If  this  were  true 
it  would  inevitably  follow  that  the  green  is  really  situated 
within  the  red  surface  of  the  paper  and  continuous  with  it. 
But,  ex  hypothesi,  what  occupies  this  particular  place  within 
the  red  background  of  the  paper  is,  in  fact,  not  a  green  but  a 
grey  speck.  The  only  conclusion  that  I  find  myself  able  to 
draw  is  that  Mr.  Alexander  is  wrong  in  identifying  sensa 
with  features  of  external  objects  existing  independently  of 
sensation  and  its  bodily  conditions.  The  existence  and 
nature  of  sensa  are  inseparable  from  correlated  processes  in 
the  nervous  system  and  sense  organs.  The  characters  of 
things  external  to  the  body  are  unaffected  by  these  processes. 
In  conclusion,  I  must  insist  on  an  objection  which,  if  it  is 
well  founded,  is  fatal  to  Mr.  Alexander's  account,  not  only  of 
illusory  perception,  but  of  ideal  revival  in  general.  It  is 
fundamental  to  his  whole  theory  that  when  the  mind  knows 
an  external  object  it  shall  communicate  with  this  through  a 
specially  appropriate  transaction  in  which  both  are  equally 
partners.  In  ordinary  sense  perception  there  is  a  continuous 
train  of  occurrences  causally  initiated  by  the  object  and 
terminating  in  a  process  taking  place  in  the  brain  of  the 
percipient.  There  ought  to  be  an  analogous  bridge  in  ideal 
revivals  and  in  illusion  between  the  independently  existing 
object  and  the  cognitive  subject.  According  to  Mr.  Alexander 
there  is  such  a  bridge  here  also.  The  only  difference  is  that 
whereas  in  normal  perception  the  common  transaction  is 
initiated  from  the  side  of  the  object,  in  illusion  or  ideal 
revival  it  is  initiated  from  the  side  of  the  subject.  In 
ordinary  perception,  the  bridge  is  thrown  across  the  stream 
from  one  bank ;  in  ideal  revival  and  illusory  perception  it  is 
thrown  across  the'  stream  from  the  opposite  bank.  It  must 
be  admitted  that  this  formula  is  very  neat.  My  difficulty  is 
that  it  seems  to  ride  rough-shod  over  the  relevant  facts.  The 
formula  could  be  justified  only  on  the  false  assumption 
that  for  example,  when,  owing  to  contrast,  we  have  a  green 
sensum  instead  of  a  grey,  there  is  initially  a  certain  process 
in  the  brain  and  organ  of  vision,  which  sets  going  a  light 
vibration  or  some  equivalent  train  of  occurrences  terminating 
in  something  which  is  really  green  and  not  grey.  Otherwise 
the  interval  between  the  percipient  and  the  independently 
existing  object  is  not  bridged  as  it  is  in  veridical  perception. 
If  it  is  said  that  no  bridge  is  required  and  that  a  certain 
cerebral  event  by  itself  suffices  to  unveil  a  certain  sensum  in 
whatever  place  and  time  this  may  exist,  I  would  ask  you  to 


412  G.  F.  STOUT  :  ALEXANDER'S  THEORY  OF  SENSE  PERCEPTION. 

consider  the  hopeless  jigsaw  puzzle  which,  on  this  view, 
would  confront  us  from  our  infancy.  Then,  sense  experience 
would  indeed  reveal  characters  and  qualities  in  the  world 
external  to  the  body,  but  would  supply  no  clue  to  determine 
where  and  when  they  existed.  It  may  be  said  that  originally 
the  process  which  discloses  a  certain  sensum  must  be  initiated 
from  the  side  of  the  object,  but  that  when  communication 
has  once  been  opened,  the  nervous  occurrence  will  suffice  by 
itself  however  it  may  arise.  But  the  explanation  does  not 
really  meet  the  difficulty.  It  is  as  if  it  were  maintained  that 
having  previously  crossed  a  stream  by  a  bridge  we  can  there- 
fore cross  it  after  the  bridge  has  been  swept  away,  provided 
only  that  a  fragment  of  it  remains  on  our  side  of  the  stream. 


II.— IS  THE  CONCEPTION  OF  THE  UNCON- 
SCIOUS OF  VALUE  IN  PSYCHOLOGY?1 

A  SYMPOSIUM  BY  G.  C.  FIELD,  F.  AVELING  AND  JOHN 

LAIRD. 

I.  BY  G.  C.  FIELD. 

IT  is  one  of  the  chief  claims  put  forward  by  the  exponents  of 
the  so-called  '  new '  Psychology  that  they  have  been  the  first 
to  recognise  seriously  the  importance  of  the  Unconscious^ 
and  the  necessity  of  assuming  unconscious  mind  or  uncon- 
scious mental  processes  to  explain  the  mental  occurrences  that 
do  take  place.  I  propose  here  to  ask  whether  this  line  of 
thought  is  really  of  value  in  Psychology.  I  do  not  intend  to 
discuss  whether  it  may  or  may  not  have  a  certain  value  as  a 
provisional  working  hypothesis  within  certain  limited  fields, 
say,  the  applied  science  of  Psycho-therapy.  The  title  confines 
us  to  a  consideration  of  its  value  to  Psychology,  in  the  proper 
sense.  Does  it  help  us  to  understand  more  clearly  what  sort 
of  thing  the  mind  is,  or  what  sort  of  thing  the  concrete 
human  being  is  ?  Does  it  afford  us  a  real  explanation,  an 
explanation  that  gives  us  real  knowledge,  of  the  mental  pro- 
cesses of  this  human  being  ?  To  these  questions  I  find"  my- 
self compelled  to  return  a  decisively  negative  answer,  well 
aware  that  by  doing  so  I  shall  at  once  write  myself  down  as 
a  hopeless  obscurantist  in  the  minds  of  many  people.  But  I 
will  try  to  give  reasons  within  the  limited  space  at  my  dis- 
posal, why  I  am  unable  to  discover  any  value  in  the  hypo- 
thesis and  why  I  maintain  further  that,  as  it  is  used  by  some 
modern  writers,  it  leads  us  to  a  positively  erroneous  idea  of 
the  nature  of  the  mind  and  of  certain  mental  processes. 

My  first  difficulty  is  one  with  which  we  are  all  familiar. 
I  repeat  it  here,  without  making  the  slightest  claim  to 
originality  in  it,  because  I  cannot  find  that  the  exponents  of 
the  '  new '  Psychology  have  so  far  shown  the  slightest  sign  of 
realising  its  seriousness  or  even  its  meaning. 

We  are  told  again  and  again  that  it  is  necessary  to  assume 
the  existence  of  the  Unconscious,  of  unconscious  regions  of 
the  mind  or  of  unconscious  mental  processes.  But  before  we 

1  Contributed  to  the  Joint  Session  of  the  Mind  Association  and  the 
Aristotelian  Society  at  Manchester,  July  14th-16th,  1922. 


414  G.  c.  FIELD: 

can  do  that,  and  still  more  before  we  can  put  forward  this 
assumption  as  a  real  explanation  of  anything,  we  must  at 
least  have  an  intelligible  idea  of  what  sort  of  thing  this  is 
which  we  have  got  to  assume.  And  it  is  here  that  the  diffi- 
culties begin.  The  point  has  of  ten  been  put.  It  is  urged  in  the 
first  place,  that  the  only  evidence  we  have  of  anything  in 
ourselves  beyond  bodily  processes  is  our  experience  of  our 
own  conscious  processes.  And  the  only  things  which  we 
can  call  '  mind '  or  '  mental '  with  any  intelligible  meaning  are 
these  conscious  processes.  Anything  in  us  which  is  neither 
conscious  nor  physical  is  therefore  something  unknowable  and 
indescribable,  or  indescribable  except  in  purely  negative 
terms.  But  if  the  Unconscious  is  thus  merely  a  negative 
idea,  something  of  which  all  that  we  can  say  is  that  it  is  not 
physical  and  not  conscious,  then  it  ceases  to  be  anything 
which  could  be  given  as  a  real  explanation.  It  is  simply  an 
X,  an  unknown  cause.  And  to  ascribe  anything  to  it  is 
simply  a  confession  of  ignorance. 

This,  of  course,  would  not  be  admitted  by  the  advocates  of 
the  claims  of  the  Unconscious.  And  we  find  them,  accord- 
ingly, continually  speaking  of  the  activities  of  the  unconscious 
mind  in  exactly  the  same  terms  as  of  the  activities  of  the 
conscious  mind,  so  that  we  hear  of  unconscious  desires, 
emotions,  wishes,  fears,  or  of  unconscious  thoughts  or 
memories.  These  unconscious  mental  processes  as  Dr. 
Ernest  Jones  tells  us  (Papers  on  Psycho- Analysis,  p.  121) 
"present  all  the  attributes  of  mental  ones,  except  that  the 
subject  is  not  aware  of  them".  And  consciousness  thus  be- 
comes, he  says,  "merely  one  attribute  of  mentality,  and  not 
an  indispensable  one".  I  have  searched  in  vain  for  a  clear 
statement  of  what  the  other  attributes  of  mentality  are  which 
these  processes  do  possess.  And  when  I  reflect  on  what  I 
mean  by  a  wish  or  an  emotion  or  a  feeling,  I  can  only  find 
that  I  know  and  think  of  them  simply  as  different  forms  of 
consciousness.  I  cannot  find  any  distinguishable  element  in 
these  experiences  which  can  be  called  consciousness  and 
separated  from  the  other  elements  even  in  thought  so  as  to 
leave  anything  determinate  behind.  And  to  ask  us  to  think 
of  something  which  has  all  the  characteristics  of  a  wish  or  a 
feeling  except  that  it  is  not  conscious  seems  to  me  like  ask- 
ing us  to  think  of  something  which  has  all  the  attributes  of 
red  or  green  except  that  it  is  not  a  colour. 

I  believe  that  everybody  really  feels  this  difficulty,  and  the 
result  is  that  many  writers  slip  into  a  way  of  talking,  and  I 
believe  at  times  of  thinking,  of  the  Unconscious  as  of  another 
conscious  person  of  exactly  the  same  kind  as  the  conscious 


VALUE   OF   THE   UNCONSCIOUS   IN   PSYCHOLOGY.          415 

personality  that  we  know,  which  exists  alongside  it  and  every 
now  and  then  affects  it  in  some  way  or  other,  so  that  to 
explain  an  event  by  referring  it  to  the  Unconscious  becomes 
just  the  same  kind  of  explanation  as  to  say  that  something 
was  done  by  John  Jones  instead  of  by  Torn  Smith.  But 
whatever  the  Unconscious  is,  it  is  not  that.  Or  else  we  are 
invited  to  take  refuge  in  spatial  metaphors,  to  talk  of  different 
levels  or  regions  of  the  mind,  and  to  think  of  it,  perhaps,  as 
a  box  with  a  false  bottom  and  a  hidden  receptacle  underneath, 
which  contains  all  sorts  of  objects.  But  this,  like  the  other 
attempt  to  describe  the  unconscious  mind,  only  ends  by  de- 
scribing something  else.  And  there  is  clearly  something 
wrong  with  a  conception  of  the  mental  which  can  only  be  de- 
scribed in  metaphors  drawn  from  the  material. 

These  are  purely  general  considerations.  To  come  to  closer 
grips  with  the  subject  it  is  necessary  to  examine  the  con- 
siderations which  are  supposed  to  make  it  necessary  to 
assume  an  Unconscious,  and  the  kind  of  occurrences  which 
are  supposed  to  be  explicable  only  on  such  an  assumption. 
And  in  this  connexion  I  should  like  to  give  a  brief  considera- 
tion to  a  typical  case,  the  case  of  claustrophobia,  of  which 
we  have  such  an  admirable  description  by  Dr.  Rivers  in  one 
of  the  Appendices  to  his  Instinct  and  the  Unconscious.  In 
this  case,  it  will  be  recalled,  an  event  took  place  in  the  early 
history  of  the  patient  which  aroused  in  him  acute  fear  at  the 
time.  The  event  was  forgotten,  so  completely  that  it  could 
not  be  recalled  by  the  ordinary  method  of  remembering.  But 
the  emotion,  or  the  tendency  to  the  emotion,  remained,  and 
was  aroused  in  the  patient  whenever  he  was  in  a  situation 
similar  to  the  original  one  in  the  respect  that  it  was  in  an 
enclosed  space. 

Now  how  does  Dr.  Eivers  describe  what  happens  here? 
Note,  in  the  first  place,  that  he  does  not  say,  as  I  should  say, 
that  the  person  is  no  longer  conscious  or  aware  of  the  past 
event.  He  says  that  the  event  itself,  which  he  calls  the  ex- 
perience, becomes  unconscious.  That  is  to  say,  he  holds  that 
the  past  event  or  experience  continues  to  exist  in  the  form  or 
in  the  place  which  he  calls  the  Unconscious.  The  evidence  for 
this  is  (1)  that  the  results  produced  by  the  event  continued  in 
the  permanent  form  of  Claustrophobia ;  (2)  that  by  the  methods 
of  Psycho-analysis  the  patient  can  be  brought  to  remember 
what  happened.  But  do  either  of  these  facts  necessitate  such 
an  assumption  ?  Or  are  they  made  any  more  intelligible  by 
this  way  of  talking  ?  Let  us  consider  them  in  turn. 

(1)  Confining  ourselves  to  what  is  absolutely  beyond 
doubt  in  the  case,  we.  can  say  firstly  that  the  past  event — of 


416  G.  c.  FIELD: 

which,  of  course,  the  person  was  fully  conscious  at  the  time 
— is  forgotten.  And  secondly,  it  is  clear  that  the  event  pro- 
duced such  an  effect  on  the  nature  or  disposition  of  the 
patient  that  in  the  future  he  always  feels  fear  in  enclosed 
spaces.  This  feeling,  again,  is  not  in  any  sense  unconscious : 
the  patient  is,  of  course,  only  too  conscious  of  it. 

But  what  I  want  to  know  is  why  the  effect  which  the 
event  produced  on  the  person  should  be  described  as  if  the 
original  event  somehow  went  on  existing  and  working  ?  And 
I  can  see  no  reason  for  it  at  all.  We  do  not  think  it  necessary 
to  talk  like  that  in  any  other  connection.  Many  events  in 
this  physical  world  produce  permanent  results  beyond  them- 
selves. But  we  do  not,  except  in  a  very  figurative  way, 
speak  of  the  event  as  continuing  to  exist  or  as  going  on 
happening  somewhere.  Nor,  indeed,  would  it  really  be  in- 
telligible to  do  so.  An  event,  whether  in  the  physical  world 
or  in  conscious  experience,  when  it  has  once  happened  is  over 
and  finished.  It  is  not  in  any  sense  a  thing  in  itself  with  a  per- 
manent existence  and  a  capacity  for  different  kinds  of  action. 
When  an  event  produces  a  result,  the  result  is  something 
other  than  itself  and  cannot  be  described  in  terms  which  imply 
the  continued  existence  of  the  event  which  caused  the  result. 

In  what  terms,  then,  can  we  describe  the  result,  in  a  case 
like  that  which  we  are  considering  ?  The  actual  result  of 
which  we  can  be  quite  certain  is  the  appearance  in  the  con- 
sciousness of  the  patient  from  time  to  time  of  a  particular 
emotion  in  particular  circumstances,  in  this  case,  the  emotion 
of  fear  in  enclosed  spaces.  And  from  that  we  conclude 
naturally  that  there  is  something  permanently  there  in  the 
nature  or  characteristics  of  the  person  which  leads  to  that 
feeling  being  aroused  in  these  circumstances.  That  is  to 
say,  we  suppose  a  certain  permanent  disposition  or  tendency 
to  feel  fear  in  enclosed  spaces. 

Dr.  Rivers  expresses  some  scorn  of  those  who  assume 
psychological  dispositions,  and  declares  that  they  are  positing 
''purely  hypothetical  factors,  when  those  open  to  direct 
observation  fail  them  ".  This  is  a  curious  reproach  from  an 
advocate  of  the  existence  of  the  Unconscious,  which  is,  if 
anything  is,  a  purely  hypothetical  factor  and  in  no  conceivable 
sense  open  to  direct  observation.  But  in  any  case  it  entirely 
misconceives  the  real  meaning  of  the  conception  of  disposi- 
tions or  tendencies.  To  begin  with,  something  of  the  kind 
is  not  a  mere  hypothesis,  but  a  necessary  inference,  and  one 
universally  made  whenever,  for  instance,  we  speak  of  a  man 
being  bad-tempered  without  meaning  necessarily  that  he  is 
at  that  moment  actually  feeling  anger.  But  it  is  also 


VALUE   OF  THE   UNCONSCIOUS  IN   PSYCHOLOGY.  417 

necessary  to  point  out  that,  if  we  know  what  we  are  doing, 
we  shall  not  make  very  exaggerated  claims  for  the  idea. 
We  shall  not,  for  instance,  make  the  claims  for  it  that  are 
made  for  the  idea  of  the  Unconscious,  nor  put  it  forward  as 
an  explanation  in  the  sense  in  which  that  idea  is  put  forward. 
It  says  simply  that  if  a  human  being,  or  indeed  any  other 
kind  of  being,  behaves  in  a  certain  way  (using  '  behave '  in 
the  widest  sense)  from  time  to  time,  there  must  be  something 
there  in  the  nature  of  that  being  which  leads  or  predisposes 
him  to  that  kind  of  behaviour  under  certain  conditions. 
There  must  be  a  permanent,  or  relatively  permanent,  mental 
structure,  to  use  Prof.  McDougall's  phrase,  which  expresses 
itself  in  that  particular  kind  of  mental  activity.  But  of  what 
sort  of  thing  this  mental  structure  is  we  know  nothing,  apart 
from  the  particular  kind  of  activity  to  which  it  leads.  We 
can  only  speak  of  it  or  think  of  it,  as  a  tendency  or  disposition 
to  this  or  that  kind  of  activity.  While  mental  function 
or  mental  activity  we  can  only  know  or  think  of  as  some  kind 
of  conscious  experience. 

We  cannot,  perhaps,  even  say  with  any  certainty  whether 
this  mental  structure  is  really  mental  or  physical.  If  we 
adopt  the  latter  alternative,  we  should  have  to  say  that  a 
certain  kind  of  arrangement  of  the  physical  structure  of  the 
brain  and  body  is  all  that  is  necessary  to  give  rise  to  certain 
kinds  of  conscious  experience  in  certain  surrounding  circum- 
stances. Such  a  view  could  certainly  not  be  dismissed  as 
untenable.  It  would,  I  take  it,  be  held  by  Prof.  Alexander 
or  by  Dr.  Bosanquet.  It  is  implied  in  the  remark  of  the 
latter,  quoted  with  approval  by  the  former;  "It  seems  to 
me  that  the  fertile  point  of  view  lies  in  taking  some  neuroses 
— not  all — as  only  complete  in  themselves  by  passing  into  a 
degree  of  psychosis  ".  We  might,  on  the  other  hand,  feel 
obliged  to  maintain  that  there  is  something,  a  definite  in- 
dividual existent,  there  which  we  can  call  a  mind  and  which 
we  believe  to  be  made  out  of  some  stuff  which  is  definitely 
not  material  and  which  we  can  properly  speak  of  as  mental 
or  psychical.  In  such  a  case,  we  should  have  to  suppose 
that  this  mind  has  certain  determinate  characteristics  which 
in  given  circumstances  will  lead  to  a  certain  kind  of  conscious 
activity.  On  this  view  we  could  never,  so  far  as  we  can  see, 
hope  to  arrive  at  any  kind  of  knowledge  of  what  this  per- 
manent structure  was  like  apart  from  the  conscious  activity 
to  which  it  leads.  Whereas  if  we  adopt  the  former  alterna- 
tive, we  could,  I  suppose,  ideally  at  least,  look  forward  to  an 
increase  in  our  knowledge  to  a  point  at  which  we  could 
know  what  kind  of  material  pattern  in  our  nervous  system 

nn 


418  G.   C.    FIELD  : 

constituted  the  permanent  tendency  to  this  or  that  kind  of 
behaviour. 

If  we  adopt  the  physical  view,  it  is  sufficiently  obvious 
that  there  is  no  need  and  no  room  for  the  Unconscious  or 
unconscious  mental  processes.  Explanation  of  anything 
that  takes  place  in  consciousness,  which  cannot  be  sufficiently 
accounted  for  by  previous  events  in  consciousness,  can  and 
must  be  looked  for  in  physical  processes.  And  this  view 
cannot  be  dismissed  lightly.  If  it  is  rejected,  it  can  only  be 
as  a  result  of  very  careful  consideration  of  very  much  wider 
questions  than  those  which  we  are  now  discussing.  As  a 
methodological  assumption  it  will  work  just  as  well  as  the 
hypothesis  of  unconscious  mental  processes.  It  is  no  doubt 
true  that,  at  any  rate  in  the  present  state  of  our  knowledge, 
these  physical  processes  are  absolutely  unknown  to  us  and  a 
pure  assumption.  But  then  so  are  the  supposed  uncon- 
scious mental  processes.  And  there  is  this  difference 
between  "them.  We  may  not  know  anything  about  the 
physical  processes  in  any  particular  case.  But  at  least  we 
have  in  general  some  idea  of  the  sort  of  things  that  we  are 
assuming.  Whereas,  if  we  postulate  unconscious  mental 
processes  we  have  not  even  any  idea  of  what  kind  of  things 
they  could  be  like.  As  suggested  above,  if  we  try  to  describe 
them  we  inevitably  find  ourselves  using  metaphors  which 
deprive  them  of  just  those  characteristics  which  we  are  most 
anxious  to  assert  of  them,  and  describing  them  as  another 
set  of  conscious  activities  or  as  material  occurrences  in  space. 

The  case  is  rather  different  if  we  believe  in  the  existence 
of  a  mind  as  a  separable  or  distinguishable  entity.  Here 
obviously,  we  can,  with  proper  precautions,  speak  of  uncon- 
scious regions  of  the  mind,  indicating  by  that  the  mental 
structure  as  opposed  to  mental  function,  the  permanent  dis- 
positions or  tendencies  in  the  mind  which  are  not  at  the 
moment  active,  the  bad  temper  of  the  man  who  is  not  angry 
at  the  moment.  But  these,  of  course,  would  be  something 
very  far  short  of  the  Unconscious  of  the  '  new  '  psychologists, 
which  is  or  involves  active  mental  processes. 

But  besides  this,  if  we  suppose  a  mind,  we  cannot  refuse 
to  admit  the  possibility  of  processes  going  on  in  that  mind 
besides  the  conscious  processes  which  we  are  aware  of.  This 
would  be  the  real  Unconscious.  But,  if  we  assert  such  pro- 
cesses, we  can  only  describe  them  negatively  by  saying  of 
them  that  they  are  processes  in  the  mind  which  are  not 
conscious.  We  can  have  no  idea  of  what  their  positive 
characteristics  are,  because  they  cannot  be  like  anything  of 
which  we  have  any  experience. 


VALUE   OF  THE   UNCONSCIOUS   IN   PSYCHOLOGY.  419 

But  is  there  really  any  necessity  thus  to  erect  an  altar  to 
the  Unknown  God  ?  It  is  generally  claimed  that  this 
necessity  arises  because  we  find  events  in  consciousness 
which  cannot  be  adequately  explained  by  preceding  events  in 
consciousness.  I  am  not  perfectly  convinced  that  the  fact  is 
as  stated.  In  the  case  of  Claustrophobia,  for  instance,  so  far 
as  I  can  see,  all  that  we  know  to  be  there  and  all  that  we 
need  assume  is,  firstly,  an  event  in  consciousness  and  then 
the  result  which  it  produces,  that  is,  a  lasting  effect  on  the 
mental  structure  of  the  patient  in  the  form  of  a  disposition 
or  tendency  to  another  kind  of  conscious  experience,  namely, 
the  emotion  of  fear  in  enclosed  spaces.  But  this  disposition 
or  tendency  only  becomes  active  when,  under  the  appropriate 
stimulus,  the  emotion  is  actually  felt.  I  can  see  no  ground 
for  supposing  that  there  is  anything  actually  occurring,  any 
active  process,  involving  some  kind  of  change  or  some  series 
of  events,  going  on  in  the  mind  outside  consciousness  alto- 
gether. Indeed  the  facts  seem  to  me  to  tell  the  other  way, 
for  the  reason  that  the  tendency  apparently  remains  un- 
changed in  character,  producing  similar  results  in  similar 
circumstances,  until  the  patient  is  cured  by  the  production 
of  an  event  which  is  definitely  in  his  consciousness,  i.e.,  the 
recollection  of  the  original  event  and  the  realisation  of  the 
connexion  of  that  with  the  emotion.  I  would  not,  however, 
assert  without  much  further  investigation  that  all  the  supposed 
cases  could  be  accounted  for  on  these  or  similar  lines.  But 
even  supposing  that  we  are  presented  with  a  case  in  which 
it  seems  necessary  to  assume  that  some  process  actually  has 
gone  on  over  a  period  of  time  which  was  not,  while  it  was 
going  on,  accessible  to  consciousness,  are  we  necessarily  bound 
to  assume  that  this  process  is  a  mental  one  ?  If  we  believe, 
as  everyone  really  does  in  practice,  in  the  interaction  of  mind 
and  body,  the  process  may  just  as  well  be  a  physical  one. 
And  the  assumption  has,  as  has  been  pointed  out  above,  at 
least  the  advantage  of  intelligibility.  It  is  only  the  dwindling 
band  of  stern  and  unbending  psycho-physical  parallelists  who 
will  feel  themselves  obliged  to  assume  that  the  process  is 
mental  in  character.  And  even  for  them,  it  is  necessary  once 
more  to  insist,  the  assumption  gives  no  information  and  makes 
nothing  any  clearer  or  more  intelligible.  It  only  has  to  be 
put  in  to  preserve  intact  the  metaphysical  doctrine  of 
parallelism. 

(2)  We  come  now  to  the  second  line  of  argument.  That 
is  the  view  that,  because  an  event  in  the  past  has  been  for- 
gotten and  can-  be  recalled  by  certain  methods,  we  must 
therefore  suppose  that  the  event  has  been  existing  all  the 


420  G.   C.   FIELD  : 

time  in  the  unconscious  regions  of  the  mind.  There  is  no 
doubt  that  the  discovery  of  these  particular  methods  of  re- 
calling forgotten  events  is  a  discovery  of  the  greatest  practical 
importance  in  the  diagnosis  and  treatment  of  psycho-neuroses. 
But  for  the  purposes  of  this  discussion,  and  in  general  con- 
sidered as  throwing  light  on  the  fundamental  problems  of  the 
nature  of  mind  and  experience,  it  does  not  appear  that  there 
is  any  difference  in  principle  between  these  special  cases  and 
any  other  case  of  remembering.  There  are  all  possible 
degrees  of  difficulty  in  recalling  different  events,  and  many 
different  methods  by  which  we  can  do  so.  The  discovery  of 
one  more  method  of  particular  efficacy  in  certain  cases  does 
not  affect  the  general  nature  of  the  processes  under  dis- 
cussion. 

The  question  really  resolves  itself  into  this :  When  an 
event  has  taken  place  of  which  we  were  aware,  and  we  re- 
member that  event  afterwards  by  whatever  method,  does 
that  mean  that  in  any  sense  the  event  has  continued  to  exist 
in  any  region  of  our  mind  all  the  time  ?  I  believe  that  in 
this  connexion,  as  in  so  many  others,  a  great  deal  of  con- 
fusion arises  from  the  use  of  that  most  dangerous  word 
1  experience '.  In  reading  Dr.  Rivers'  book,  for  instance,  I 
find  him  constantly  speaking  of  an  unconscious  experience 
where  I  should  speak  of  a  forgotten  past  event,  with  the 
apparent  implication  that  the  whole  event  is  in  some  way  a 
mental  occurrence. 

With  this  we  are  obviously  face  to  face  with  the  great 
question  of  the  relation  of  mind  to  its  objects.  In  any  act  of 
knowing  what  is  "  in  "  the  mind,  or  mental  (for  I  can  con- 
ceive of  no  meaning  of  the  spatial  metaphor  '  in  '  the  mind, 
except  that  it  is  mental  in  character),1  and  what  is  '  outside ' 
the  mind  or  physical  ?  This  is,  of  course,  one  of  the  burning 
questions  of  modern  Philosophy,  and  obviously,  I  cannot 
discuss  it  here.  But  I  mention  it  because  it  seems  to  me 
obvious  that  it  is  a  question  on  which  we  must  make  up  our 
minds  before  we  can  begin  to  think  clearly  in  Psychology  at 
all.  For  surely  a  science  which  attempts  to  describe  in  any 
way  the  nature  of  the  mind  or  consciousness  or  the  mental, 
is  bound  to  give  a  clear  account  of  what  is  mental  and  what 
is  not  mental  in  such  a  typical  event  as  an  act  of  cognition. 
Unless  we  are  clear  about  this  we  cannot  possibly  arrive  at 

1  No  doubt  on  certain  views,  such  as  those  held  by  Prof.  Alexander,  we 
can  speak  of  an  object  having  spatial  relations  to  the  mind.  "In"  the 
mind,  then,  would  mean  strictly  in  the  brain.  But,  of  course,  there  is  na 
question  of  a  physical  object,  of  which  we  are  aware,  being  inside  the 
brain. 


VALUE   OF   THE   UNCONSCIOUS   IN  PSYCHOLOGY.  421 

a  clear  idea  of  what  kind  of  thing  we  believe  the  mind  and 
mental  processes  to  be.  We  cannot  get  out  of  it  by  dis- 
missing the  question  as  Metaphysics,  just  because  its  solution 
demands  a  considerable  amount  of  effort  and  hard  thinking. 

If  we  take,  as  I  do,  a  Eealist  view  of  these  matters,  it  is 
obvious  that  it  is  impossible  to  accept  any  description  of  the 
'  experience '  as  continuing  to  exist  and  to  act  in  the  mind. 
This  way  of  thinking  of  an  '  experience  '  as  a  detached  ob- 
ject working  on  its  own  in  this  way  or  that  would  have 
difficulties,  I  should  imagine,  for  any  school  of  thought. 
But  the  special  objection  of  the  Eealist  would  clearly  be 
to  the  failure  to  distinguish  the  object  known  from  the 
knowing  of  it.  This  confusion  is  particularly  easy  in  the 
case  of  memory.  If  we  see  a  dog,  it  needs  a  considerable 
amount  of  training  in  certain  schools  of  Philosophy  for  us  to 
persuade  ourselves  that  the  dog  is  '  in  '  our  minds.  But  when 
we  remember  a  dog  that  we  had  seen,  as  the  dog  is  not 
obviously  '  there,'  it  is  much  easier  for  us  to  imagine  that  the 
poor  animal  has  somehow  fallen  into  the  '  well  of  memory/ 
(or  got  shut  up  in  the  '  storehouse '),  and  that  we  are  now 
engaged  in  fishing  him  out.  It  is  only  when  we  drop  spatial 
metaphors,  and  realise  that  a  thing  cannot  be  '  in  '  the  mind 
unless  it  is  mental  in  character,  that  it  becomes  clear  that  a 
dog  or  any  other  object  that  is  not  mental  when  we  see  it 
certainly  cannot  entirely  change  its  nature  and  become  mental 
when  we  remember  it.  There  are  plenty  of  difficulties  and 
obscurities  in  the  nature  of  the  process  of  remembering,  on 
any  theory.  But  I  am  perfectly  sure  that  on  no  theory  are 
any  of  these  difficulties  removed  or  lessened  by  supposing 
that  the  object  or  event  remembered  is  in  any  sense  '  in  '  the 
mind. 

I  find  this  way  of  thinking  constantly  appearing  in  all 
attempts  to  describe  the  Unconscious,  as  when  we  are  told 
by  the  Psycho-Analysts  that  the  content  of  the  Unconscious 
consists  of  repressed  infantile  experiences.  No  doubt,  for 
their  particular  practical  purposes  these  metaphors  may  be 
harmless  and  even,  up  to  a  point,  helpful.  But  when  they 
are  put  forward  as  a  serious  account  of  the  nature  of  the 
mind  or  mental  processes,  they  become,  in  my  view,  mislead- 
ing and  mischievous. 

I  have  left  myself  no  space  for  a  detailed  examination  of 
any  other  case  where  it  is  supposed  that  we  must  assume 
Unconscious  mental  processes.  I  think  there  are  few  of 
them  to  which  some,  at  any  rate,  of  the  above  considerations 
would  not  apply.  But  I  cannot  help  being  struck,  in  reading 
the  accounts  of  these  cases,  by  the  slightness  of  the  evidence 


422  G.  c.  FIELD: 

that  seems  sometimes  to  be  accepted  that  the  mental  process 
really  is  unconscious.  After  all,  with  all  our  tests,  we  have 
in  the  end  to  come  for  our  final  evidence  for  the  presence  or 
absence  of  anything  in  the  consciousness  of  a  person  to  the 
statements  of  the  person  himself.  And  we  all  know  how 
easy  it  is  to  misdescribe  what  is  really  going  on  in  our  own 
consciousness.  This  is  so  even  with  a  perfectly  honest  at- 
tempt ;  and  when  we  take  into  account  what  Jowett  described 
as  "the  amount  of  good  hard  lying  that  goes  on  in  the 
world,"  the  statements  of  a  neurotic  patient  do  not  seem  a 
very  certain  foundation  on  which  to  build  our  conclusions. 
Nor,  for  the  matter  of  that,  are  the  statements  of  anybody 
else  in  all  cases.  We  most  of  us  at  one  time  or  another 
know  what  it  is  to  have  thoughts  or  feelings  which  we  should 
be  very  loath  to  put  into  words.  But  they  are  none  the  less 
conscious  for  that.  This  is  really  a  minor  point.  But  apart 
from  that,  there  are,  of  course,  at  any  moment  many  things 
going  on  in  our  consciousness,  just  as  there  are  many  things 
in  the  outside  world  within  our  field  of  vision,  on  which  our 
attention  is  not  focussed.  We  do  not,  therefore,  think  about 
them ;  we  do  not  recognise  their  implications  or  connect  them 
up  with  the  rest  of  our  experience.  And,  therefore,  we  often 
do  not  remember  that  they  were  there  even  a  few  minutes 
afterwards.  But  once  more  they  are  certainly  conscious  pro- 
cesses at  the  time  they  take  place. 

These  are  apparently  what  Dr.  Rivers  calls  "  sub-conscious 
processes  ".  At  least,  so  I  judge  by  his  description  of  these 
latter  as  "  processes  which  only  differ  from  other  mental  pro- 
cesses in  the  lesser  degree  of  distinctness  and  clearness  with 
which  they  can  be  observed  ".  And  he  criticises  those  who 
speak  of  such  processes  as  "failing  to  recognise  that  they 
were  only  evading  a  difficulty  by  clinging  to  a  simulacrum  of 
the  conscious,  the  existence  of  which  was  just  as  hypothetical 
as  any  of  the  constructions  of  the  thorough-going  advocate 
of  the  Unconscious  ".  Unless  I  entirely  misunderstand  this, 
it  seems  to  me  really  an  amazing  statement.  For  it  char- 
acterises as  purely  hypothetical  the  familiar  distinction  be- 
tween the  focus  and  the  margin  of  consciousness,  which  I 
should  have  called  an  obvious  fact  of  experience  which  any- 
one of  us  could  verify  for  himself  with  the  utmost  ease.  If  I 
am  right,  it  is  clearly  a  fact  of  importance  for  the  present 
discussion,  because  it  means  that  there  are  always  a  certain 
number  of  conscious  processes  going  on  and  a  certain  number 
of  objects  of  which  we  are  aware  which  we  may  not  remember 
about  at  a  later  time.  This  makes  it  impossible  to  say  with 
any  certainty  that  conscious  processes  at  one  time  cannot  be 


VALUE   OF  THE   UNCONSCIOUS   IN   PSYCHOLOGY  423 

adequately  explained  by  previous  processes  which  were  just 
as  conscious,  because  we  can  never  be  sure  about  what  previous 
processes  did  actually  occur.  We  can  never  assert  positively 
that  the  explanation  of  anything  must  be  looked  for  in  some- 
thing outside  the  "  stream  of  consciousness  "  altogether,  be- 
cause we  never  have  exhaustive  knowledge  of  all  that  is  or 
has  been  in  the  "  stream  of  consciousness  ".  And  if  this  is 
true  it  certainly  weakens  seriously  the  alleged  necessity  of 
assuming  unconscious  mental  processes  as  an  explanation. 

This,  then,  is  a  very  brief  and  inadequate  outline  of  my 
case  against  the  idea  of  the  Unconscious  or  of  Unconscious 
mental  processes.  I  cannot  accept  it  because  I  cannot  attach 
any  meaning  to  it  and  cannot  see  any  necessity  for  it. 
Further,  in  the  modern  form,  it  seems  to  me  to  mix  up  many 
things  or  many  problems  which  ought  to  be  kept  separate  ; 
to  confuse,  for  instance,  the  problem  of  the  nature  of  mental 
dispositions  with  that  of  the  nature  of  the  act  of  memory. 
And  I  believe  that  it,  at  any  rate  in  this  form,  implies  a  false 
view  of  the  nature  of  mind,  of  the  relation  of  mind  and  body, 
and  of  the  relation  of  the  knower  and  the  known  in  an  act 
of  cognition.  But  I  should  not  like  to  leave  the  subject 
without  a  word  of  tribute  to  the  work  of  many  of  the  writers 
who  have  advocated  this  idea.  Particularly  to  Dr.  Rivers, 
whose  book  seems  to  me,  if  I  may  say  so  without  impertin- 
ence, one  of  the  ablest  and  sanest  of  the  statements  of  modern 
tendencies  in  Psychology.  Apart  from  this  unfortunate 
business  of  the  Unconscious,  I  have  learnt  more  from  it  than 
from  almost  any  other  recent  work  on  these  subjects. 


II.  BY  F.  AVELING. 

I  MAY  say  at  the  outset  of  this  small  contribution  to  our 
symposium  that  I  am  largely  in  agreement  with  Mr.  Field. 
When  he  asks,  at  the  beginning  of  his  paper,  whether  the 
conception  of  the  Unconscious  helps  us  to  understand  more 
clearly  what  sort  of  thing  the  mind  is,  or  what  sort  of  thing 
the  concrete  human  being  is,  I  am  inclined  to  believe  that  it 
does  not  take  us  very  far,  and  certainly  not  to  the  point  of 
adequate  philosophical  explanations  per  causas.  But  I  do 
not  agree  with  him  in  thinking  that  it  leads  to  a  positively 
erroneous  idea  of  the  nature  of  the  mind  and  of  certain  mental 
processes.  It  is  true  that  Mr.  Field  qualifies  his  statement 
with  the  words  "  as  it  is  used  by  some  modern  writers  ".  I 
shall  not  undertake  to  defend  any  views  that  may  be  held  as 


424  F.  AVELING: 

to  the  Unconscious ;  but  merely  to  show  that  there  is  a  sense 
in  which  the  conception  may  be  valid  and  of  service  in 
psychology.  But,  in  order  to  do  this,  it  is  necessary  to 
examine  at  least  two  of  the  terms  in  the  enunciation  of  the 
present  symposium  which  need  definition  ;  and  with  regard 
to  one  of  them — the  Unconscious  itself — Mr.  Field  finds  that 
he  can  attach  no  meaning  to  it  at  all.  It  may  be  an  un- 
fortunate term  ;  it  may  have  led,  and  lead,  to  misunderstand- 
ings ;  but  it  has  a  meaning  for  empirical  psychologists  none 
the  less  which  it  will  be  my  task  to  consider  in  the  course  of 
the  present  paper.  I  shall  use  the  term  "  Unconscious," 
then,  to  signify  something  which  is  experiential  in  character ; 
that  is  to  say,  something  which  at  one  time  actually  formed 
part  of  experience,  and  of  which  the  subject  of  the  experience 
may  also  have  been  aware ;  something  which,  in  appropriate 
conditions,  may  (or  may  again)  come  to  awareness ;  some- 
thing, however,  which  is  not  now  part  of  awareness.  To  add 
to  this  characterisation  of  the  Unconscious  that  this  some- 
thing, not  now  part  of  awareness,  may  only  be  made  part  of 
awareness  by  means  of  methods  such  as  those  of  psycho- 
analysis, is  merely  to  specify  a  more  generic  use  of  the  term. 
This  signification  "  links  up  "  the  Unconscious,  by  way  of  the 
Sub-conscious  and  the  minimal,  with  the  maximal  degree  of 
awareness.  I  am  not  now  concerned  with  that  other  Un- 
conscious which,  of  its  nature,  can  never  directly  form  part 
of  awareness  at  all — that  "unconscious  psychic"  which  is 
essential  or  dispositional  rather  than  experiential ;  which  yet 
may  be  necessary  as  a  concept,  as  is  matter  or  force  in 
physics  or  substance  in  metaphysics,  for  a  final  completion 
and  explanation  of  the  science  of  psychology. 

A  second  term  which  requires  definition  is  "  Psychology  "  ; 
for  it  is  used  ambiguously.  It  may  mean  psychology  the 
science  in  the  strict  sense  ;  or  it  may  mean  psychology  in 
the  older,  transcendental  and  metaphysical  sense.  Mr.  Field 
apparently  accepts  it  in  the  latter  of  the  two  meanings.  His 
universe  of  discourse  is  a  metaphysical  one— and  perfectly 
legitimately  so.  But  the  psychologists  who  find  the  concep- 
tion of  the  Unconscious  useful  in  their  scientific  work,  con- 
ceive psychology  itself  in  an  empirical,  non-transcendental 
manner.  I  believe  that  in  such  a  distinction  lies  the  explana- 
tion of  the  divergence  of  views  as  to  the  value  for  psychology 
of  the  conception  of  the  Unconscious. 

There  is  no  need  to  turn  to  the  region  of  abnormal  or 
pathological  psychology  for  data  to  support  this  conception. 
Mr.  Field  appears  to  allow  that  it  may  be  of  some  practical 
value  there ;  and,  when  he  gets  to  close  grips  with  his  topic, 


VALUE   OF  THE   UNCONSCIOUS   IN  PSYCHOLOGY.          425 

he  examines  the  case  of  claustrophobia,  cited  by  Dr.  Eivers, 
as  a  sample  of  one  of  those  "  occurrences  which  are  supposed 
to  be  explicable  only  on  such  an  assumption ".  But  he 
implies  elsewhere  in  his  paper  that  this  region  of  the  patho- 
logical is  debarred  to  the  theoretical  psychologist  as  not 
belonging  to  psychology  in  the  "proper  sense".  Against 
such  an  implication  I  may  allow  myself  to  make  a  protest  in 
passing,  on  the  ground  that  the  abnormal  in  consciousness  is 
as  much  the  subject-matter  of  psychology  as  is  the  normal. 
If,  indeed,  the  conception  of  the  Unconscious  should  be  one 
which  arises  only  in  connexion  with  abnormal  processes,  it 
would  still  have  rights  of  citizenship  within  psychology  in 
the  "proper  sense".  But  the  conception  arises,  though 
perhaps  in  a  less  restricted  and  technical  sense,  in  psychology 
in  connexion  with  the  ordinary  processes  of  everyday  mental 
life ;  and  it  is  as  useful  there  as  it  is  anywhere  else.  So  we 
may  well  limit  ourselves  in  our  consideration — though  I  do 
not  agree  that  the  title  of  the  symposium  defines  these  limits 
for  us — to  an  examination  of  the  normal  processes  of  con- 
sciousness. 

I  conceive  the  starting-point  of  the  science  of  psychology 
to  be  an  examination  of  the  data  of  consciousness  :  i.e.,  aware- 
ness ;  and  its  end  a  statement  of  the  laws  of  their  concomit- 
ances and  successions.  When  all  the  data  have  been 
examined — the  "  objective  contents,"  and  the  "  static  "  and 
"  dynamic  "  states — and  when  the  laws  have  been  formulated, 
it  will  be  found  that  certain  hypothetical  elements  have  been 
necessarily  introduced  to  complete  and  round  off  the  whole 
after  the  manner  of  a  science.  But  those  hypothetical 
elements  will  be — or  should  be — appropriate  to  the  original 
data.  They  should  not,  unless  it  is  impossible  to  complete 
the  science  otherwise,  introduce  characters  which  the  original 
data  do  not  display. 

Later  on,  of  course,  certain  concepts  may  be  introduced 
and  explanatory  theory  devised  to  account  for  the  occurrence 
of  the  data  in  question  ;  or  for  the  fact  that  it  has  been 
found  possible  to  state  any  "laws"  in  their  regard;  or  for 
the  further  fact  that  empirical  beliefs  have  been  discovered 
among  them,  the  objects  of  which  are  trans-empirical.  But 
that  is  not,  strictly  speaking,  a  matter  with  which  psychology, 
considered  as  a  science,  has  any  concern. 

What  is,  however  of  the  greatest  importance  to  observe  is 
that  all  the  data,  or  "  processes,"  of  consciousness  which 
come  to  awareness  are,  in  one  respect  at  least,  of  exactly  the 
same  character.  They  are  all  mental.  The  object  known, 
as  known,  is  as  much  subjective  as  is  the  static  state  of 


426  F.   AVELING  : 

pleasure  or  the  dynamic  state  of  intention.  The  latter  are 
as  much  objective  as  the  first.  Indeed,  none,  properly 
speaking,  as  far  as  they  are  considered  as  conscious  facts  or 
processes,  can  be  characterised  as  either  objective  or  subjec- 
tive, except  in  so  far  as  these  are  useful  categories  for  the 
classification  of  mental  occurrences.  They  are  all  without 
exception  essentially  mental  in  character.  From  the  psycho- 
logical point  of  view,  and  regarded  solely  as  conscious  pro- 
cesses, the  subject-object  distinction  seems  to  be  out  of  place. 
Everything  is  subject,  or  everything  is  object,  as  you  please. 

If  psychology  is  to  be  a  science,  then,  it  must  keep  to  this 
point  of  view ;  for  that,  after  all,  is  no  more  than  the  general 
method  of  science. 

We  may  find  a  parallel  in  the  physical  sciences.  In  all 
these  abstraction  is  made  from  the  fact  that  the  data  with 
which  they  deal  are  in  reality  mental;  and  these  are  con- 
sidered as  if  they  had  a  real  existence  in  a  world  indifferent 
to  mind.  That  is  the  method  of  these  sciences ;  and  those 
who  profess  them  do  not  trouble  about  its  justification,  which 
— as  far  as  they  consider  it  at  all — they  leave  to  the  philo- 
sophers. But,  in  arranging  and  explaining  the  data,  con- 
sidered thus  abstractly,  each  science  keeps  to  its  own  point 
of  view ;  each  introduces  hypothetical  elements,  where  these 
are  necessary,  appropriately  similar  in  kind  to  the  original 
data,  to  complete  and  round  off  the  whole ;  and,  finally,  each 
turns  to  philosophy  for  an  explanation  by  trans-empirical 
concepts. 

Consider,  for  example,  the  flight  of  an  arrow,  and  that  of  a 
bullet  fired  from  a  rifle.  In  the  one  case,  there  may  be  data 
observable  from  the  moment  when  the  arrow  is  fitted  to  the 
bow-string  to  that  when  it  is  fixed  in  the  target.  In  the 
latter  case,  there  may  be  no  such  data ;  but  ballistics  assigns 
relative  position,  as  part  of  the  hypothetical  data,  throughout 
the  whole  course  of  the  flight.  What  has  been  said  as  to 
completion  by  hypothetical  elements  is  largely,  if  not  entirely, 
true  of  the  physical  sciences  taken  singly.  It  is  altogether 
true  of  them  taken  as  a  group.  "Physical"  occurrences  are 
observed  and  related;  "  physical  "  laws  are  formulated;  and 
the  whole  is  completed  with  hypothetical  "  physical  "  data, 
and  ultimately  with  "  physical  "  concepts,  the  character  of 
which  is  strictly  non-mental. 

Psychology,  as  a  science,  pursues  a  similar  method.  It 
completes  its  observations  and  relating  of  data  with  hypo- 
thetical elements  similar  in  kind  to  the  original  data.  And 
it  is  here  that  the  conception  of  the  Unconscious  naturally 
arises.  Whatever  it  is,  it  must  be  appropriate  to  the  data ; 


VALUE   OF  THE   UNCONSCIOUS   IN  PSYCHOLOGY.          427 

that  is,  it  must  be  mental,  or  "  conscious  ".  It  is  no  real  ob- 
jection to  urge  against  this  conception  of  the  Unconscious 
that  its  nature  cannot  be  known,  as  things  are  known  by 
inspection ;  for  that  is  true  as  well  of  the  physical  hypothetical 
elements — and  indeed  also  of  the  physical  concepts.  The 
Unconcious  can  only  be  known  by  reflexion  upon  what  it 
does.  It  provides  a  nexus,  or  principle,  for  the  explanation 
of  the  processes  which  occur  in  awareness.  Its  nature,  then, 
will  be  consonant  with  these ;  and  it  will  be  inferred  from 
these.  There  is,  however,  another  than  the  theoretical 
reason  given  above  for  the  assertion  of  the  conception  of  the 
Unconscious.  And  it  is  this.  The  field  of  awareness  itself 
is  distinguishable  into  areas  or  zones  of  differing  degrees  of 
clearness — or,  rather,  is  continuously  differentiated  in  this 
respect  from  the  point  of  maximal  to  a  margin  of  minimal 
clearness.  Direction  of  the  "Attention  "  can  shift  the  focal 
point  of  clearness  from  one  point  of  the  field  to  another  ; 
indeed,  can  cause  to  rise  into  the  focus  a  content  which  was 
not  at  the  moment  in  the  field  at  all,  but  in  Sub-conciousness 
—as  when  one  is  trying  to  recall,  and  successfully  recalls,  a 
forgotten  name.  These  two  observable  facts  lend  support  to 
the  conception  of  the  Unconscious  as  continuous  with  aware- 
ness and  the  Sub-conscious,  and  in  some  respects,  at  any  rate, 
as  obeying  the  same  laws.  For  the  unconscious  processes 
can  come  to  awareness,  by  the  use  of  appropriate  methods, 
in  a  similar  way  to  the  Sub-conscious  processes,  and  can  be 
made  to  enter  the  focal  point  in  a  way  similar  to  that  in 
which  the  marginal  processes  can. 

I  am  here,  of  course,  referring  principally  to  the  Uncon- 
scious in  the  generic  sense  indicated  above,  as  consisting  of 
that  of  which  we  may  or  may  not  have  been,  but  are  not  now 
aware.  In  the  specific,  technical  and  psycho-pathological 
sense,  the  Unconscious  cannot  thus  be  directly  brought  into 
the  field  of  awareness  by  any  of  the  ordinary  means  at  the 
disposal  of  the  subject,  or  patient.  Indeed,  as  Dr.  Ernest 
Jones  points  out,  "  the  attempt  to  explore  them  (unconscious 
processes)  and  make  them  conscious  is  always  accompanied 
by  manifestations  of  active  opposition  on  the  part  of  the 
subject."  (Symposium,  "Why  is  the  Unconscious  uncon- 
scious ?  "  BJ.P.,  Vol.  9,  Part  2,  October,  1918.)  This  refers 
to  that  group  of  unconscious  experiential  processes  which, 
whether  racial  or  personal,  apparently  lies  beyond  the  power 
of  translation  into  awareness,  or  recall,  on  the  part  of  the 
subject.  Yet,  even  here,  these  dissociated  processes  would 
still  appear  to  be  in  continuity  with  the  Unconscious  in  the 
generic  sense,  since,  though  they  cannot  be  brought  to 


428  F.  AVELING: 

awareness  by  the  patient,  they  can  become  processes  in 
awareness  by  the  use,  on  the  part  of  the  analyst,  of  methods 
by  which  the  active  opposition  of  the  patient  is  overcome. 
And  the  methods  used  do  not  appear  to  involve  any  new 
laws,  but  only  to  apply  the  old  ones  with  good  effect. 

Mr.  Field  finds  himself  unable  to  accept  this  conception, 
and  he  puts  forward  the  two  alternative  views,  as  at  least 
conceivable  accounts  of  the  matter ;  that,  on  the  one  hand, 
consciousness  may  depend  upon  the  physical  structure  of  the 
brain  and  body ;  on  the  other,  that  it  may  be  the  function  of 
a  relatively  permanent  mental  structure.  Philosophically, 
I  might  agree  with  him  in  accepting  one  of  these  alternatives. 
But  the  first  of  these  views  is  inacceptable  to  the  empirical 
science  of  psychology  as  an  explanation,  because  it  goes  out- 
side the  data,  and  indeed  makes  use  of  "data"  that  not  only 
are  not  given,  but  are  even  supposed  to  be  of  a  totally  different 
character  to  those  that  are  given.  The  second  view  is  no 
less  inacceptable,  for  it  seems  to  involve  the  denial  that 
statements  of  scientific  laws  are  possible  in  psychology  at  all. 
If  the  webs  of  antecedents  and  consequents  are  not  complete, 
there  can  be  no  such  statement.  I  take  it  that  no  empirical 
psychologist  —  not  even  the  empirical  psychopathologist — 
holds  of  the  unconscious  processes  that  they  are  in  everything 
identical  with  those  which  enter  into  the  region  of  awareness. 
The  use  of  the  term  Unconscious  would  negaige  any  such 
supposition.  But  I  take  it  also  that  no  philosopher  would 
conceive  of  "  mental  structure,"  and  "  function  "  as  some- 
thing which  necessarily  precludes  the  possibility  of  the 
empirical  conception.  Mental  structure  might  conceivably 
underlie  both  Awareness  and  Unconsciousness ;  and  both 
might  be  its  function.  It  appears  to  me  that  a  very  old 
philosophical  distinction  may  usefully  be  applied  with  regard 
to  this  matter;  that  the  potential  must  be  distinguished 
from  the  actual ;  and  that  the  processes  which  occur  in  the 
region  of  awareness  are  the  actual  analogues  of  those  potential 
processes  which  are  held  to  belong  to  the  region  of  the  Un- 
conscious. In  how  far  the  potential  processes  may  resemble 
the  actual  seems  to  me  to  be  a  rather  otiose  question — one 
that  should  not,  and  certainly  need  not,  be  raised.  It  may 
be  that  they  are  identical  with  these  save  in  the  property  of 
being  "conscious".  To  suppose  that  would  be  to  imagine 
these  processes  in  some  respect  after  the  manner  in  which 
conscious  ideas  were  imagined  in  Associationism.  It  may 
be  that  they  resemble  them  in  no  such  sense  at  all.  Or  it 
may  be  that  they  resemble — I  adopt  the  distinction  from  Dr. 
Bivers's  contribution  to  the  symposium  already  cited — the 


VALUE   OF  THE   UNCONSCIOUS   IN  PSYCHOLOGY.  429 

instincts,  as  contrasted  with  the  "  discriminative  and  in- 
telligent "  higher  processes  of  awareness. 

Now,  this  last  possibility  appears  to  offer  some  help  to- 
wards denning  the  Unconscious  in  such  a  way  that  it  will  be 
acceptable  both  to  the  empirically  methodological  psycholo- 
gists and  to  those  whose  principal  interests  lead  them  to  take 
a  metaphysical  view  of  the  question.  Every  complex  of 
conscious  awareness  consists  of  three  discriminable  elements 
or  aspects.  In  every .  conscious  complex  we  may  discover 
cognition,  conation,  and  affection.  It  is  only  by  abstraction 
that  they  can  be  separated,  though  any  one  of  them  may,  at 
any  given  moment,  dominate  the  other  two.  For  pure 
empirical  psychology  each  of  these  is  an  element  or  aspect 
in  its  own  right,  and  of  equivalent  value  to  any  other ;  for 
each  is  a  discriminable  element  or  aspect  in  the  given  of  that 
experience  of  which  we  are  aware.  But  there  are  discover- 
able limiting  cases  in  which  the  cognitive  element  or  aspect 
so  sinks  in  intensity  that  the  experiencing  subject  is  hardly, 
if  indeed  at  all,  aware  of  it,  the  while  he  is  actually  and 
vividly  living  the  experience  of  an  affective  state  brought 
about  by  a  stimulus  which  is  capable  of  producing  both. 
Similarly,  the  cognitive  and  affective  elements  or  aspects  in 
a  complex  may  conceivably  be  minimal — indeed,  in  certain 
phases  of  the  act  of  choice  seem  actually  to  be  minimal. 
And  the  effect  which  a  previous  volition  (as  such)  now  forgotten 
(or  sunk  beneath  the  level  of  conscious  awareness  and 
functioning  as  a  "  mental  set ")  has  upon  subsequent  pro- 
cesses of  awareness  is  well  known.  Evidence  of  this  kind  is 
abundant  in  such  researches  as  those  of  Ach,  Michotte  and 
Priim,  and  others. 

But  if  cognitional  awareness  can  sink  to  a  minimum, 
leaving  a  lived  experience  of  affection ;  and  if  conscious 
volition  can  become  unconscious  and  still  influence  the  pro- 
cesses which  develop  in  awareness ;  it  would  seem  that  we 
have  some  direct  evidence  that  the  Unconscious  is  a  valid 
conception  and  a  useful  one  for  psychology.  For,  here  again, 
the  processes  of  which  we  are  aware  and  those  of  which  we 
are  not  aware,  or  have  ceased  to  be  aware,  seem  to  obey  the 
same  laws,  functioning  indifferently  as  antecedents  to  the 
same  sort  of  consequents,  and  vice  versa.  An  impulsive  act 
is  in  this  precisely  similar  to  a  voluntary  act  or  to  an  act  of 
choice ;  the  only  difference  lying  in  the  condition  of  the 
voluntary  act  (that  there  is  prevision  of  the  end) ;  and  in 
that  of  the  act  of  choice  (that  the  realisation  of  the  volition 
is  conditioned  by  the  appearance  of  the  alternatives  between 
which,  and  the  discussion  of  the  motives  according  to  the 


430  F.   AVELING: 

evaluation  of  which,  it  is  to  be  made).  But  the  volition 
may  not  be  a  conscious  one,  and  generally  is  not,  when 
the  act  of  choice  takes  place.  For  such  reasons  as  these 
all  three  processes  (including  the  impulsive  or  instinctive) 
have  been  classified  under  the  head  of  volitional  acts.  Now, 
instinct  is  generally  supposed  to  be  blind  or  unconscious  in 
its  teleological  character ;  yet  it  is  not  too  much  to  say  that 
it  has  every  mark  of  consciousness,  and  purposive  conscious- 
ness, as  far  as  its  effects  are  concerned.  So  much  is  this 
evident  that  instinct  has  been  accounted  for  on  the  ground 
that  it  is  "  lapsed  intelligence  ".  Without  wishing  to  adopt 
that  theory,  there  would  seem  to  be  no  reason  to  reject  a 
possible  view  which  would  make  of  it  a  lapsed  conscious 
awareness  of  some  sort,  not  unlike  that  which  might  be 
asserted  of  a  consciously  (and,  originally  volitionally)  ac- 
quired habit  which,  later  on,  comes  to  be  carried  out 
automatically  and  unconsciously.  Some  such  line  of  con- 
sideration as  this  would  allow  us  to  link  up  what  I  have 
distinguished  as  Unconsciousness  in  the  generic  sense  with 
Unconsciousness  in  the  more  specific  sense  in  which  the 
term  is  used  by  the  psychopathologists.  And  thus,  by 
opposing  original  instincts  and  original  mere  experiences, 
together  with  complexes  which  have  been  extruded  from 
personal  awareness  by  reason  of  the  many  and  varied  sanctions 
of  'civilised  life,  to  complexes  which  have  not  been  so  extruded, 
we  should  understand  how  those  conflicts  which  may  issue 
in  the  morbid  processes  studied  in  psychopathology  come  to 
be  established  in  the  whole  mentality. 

Instinct,  as  a  native  impulsion  anterior  to  all  individual 
experience,  though  there  may  be  a  cognitive  antecedent  to 
energise  it,  is  certainly  not  conscious  until  it  has  functioned. 
But  it  links  up  with  conscious  volitions  through,  and  in 
continuity  with,  "mental  set".  In  otheri  words,  there  is,  or 
at  least  can  be  conceived,  a  continuity  between  the  volitional 
processes  which  occur  in  awareness  and  those  which  do  not 
so  occur.  And  this  may  most  easily  be  conceived  as  a  con- 
tinuity of  the  similar  in  kind,  as  well  as  a  continuity  due  to 
the  fact  that  both,  again,  may  be  antecedents  or  consequents 
in  similar  sequences,  i.e.,  both  obey  similar  laws.  Whether 
actual  or  potential,  then,  whether  conscious  or  unconscious, 
both  cognitive  and  volitional  processes  exemplify  the  same 
laws,  and  may  at  least  be  conceived  as  in  some  sense  similar. 

A  parallel  line  of  consideration  might  be  pursued  with 
regard  to  the  affective  aspect  of  the  complex ;  and  on  this, 
no  doubt,  the  psychoanalysts  lay  great  stress. 

But  I  need  not,  perhaps,  elaborate   further  than  I  have 


VALUE   OF   THE   UNCONSCIOUS   IN   PSYCHOLOGY          431 

done  to  show  that  the  conception  of  the  Unconscious  has  a 
value  for  psychology  the  science.  It  is  no  more  than  a  con- 
ception in  which  sequences  which  are  incomplete  to  inspec- 
tion are  completed  by  the  assumption  of  the  existence  of 
processes  or  elements  of  a  similar  character,  barring  the  one 
note  of  awareness.  But  these  processes  or  elements  can  be 
made  actual  even  as  regards  awareness.  They  may  there- 
fore be  considered  as  potential  processes  or  elements  of 
awareness.  To  explain  the  facts  in  any  other  way  than  by 
assuming  potentially  empirical  data  of  a  similar  kind  to  that 
which  is  given  is  to  step  beyond  the  boundaries  of  the  science. 
To  assume  a  mental  structure  capable  of  functioning  because 
of  its  tendencies  is,  for  the  empiricist,  either  to  assert  what 
has  been  suggested  in  this  paper  or  to  assert  nothing  know- 
able  or  verifiable.  For  what  is  a  tendency,  and  how  can  it 
be  denned  save  by  referring  to  that  actual  towards  the 
realisation  of  which  it  is  a  tendency  ?  To  suppose  that 
tendencies  cause  awareness,  using  the  term  in  its  transcen- 
dental sense,  or  that  the  mental  structure  causes  awareness 
through  its  tendencies,  seems,  from  an  empiric  point  of  view, 
to  have  far  less  meaning  than  to  suppose  that  a  hypothetical 
Unconsciousness  causes  awareness  in  the  scientific  accepta- 
ton  of  the  word  cause.  For  transcendental  causes  cannot 
be  observed. 

And  further  the  criticism  aimed  at  the  theory  in  question 
by  Mr.  Field — that  it  leads  to  the  conception  "  of  the  Uncon- 
scious as  of  another  conscious  person  of  exactly  the  same 
kind  as  the  conscious  personality  we  know,  which  exists 
alongside  it  and  every  now  and  then  affects  it  in  some  way 
or  other,  so  that  to  explain  an  event  by  referring  it  to  the 
Unconscious  becomes  just  the  same  kind  of  explanation  as 
to  say  that  something  was  done  by  John  Jones  instead  of  by 
Tom  Smith," — can  only  be  a  valid  criticism  if  it  does  in  fact 
necessarily  lead  to  such  a  conception.  And  it  does  not,  I 
suggest,  lead  to  that  at  all  if  the  whole  matter  is  treated 
empirically ;  though  I  admit  that  it  may  lead  to  it  if  aware- 
ness and  Unconsciousness  and  cause  are  taken  in  their  meta- 
physical implications. 

It  can  only  be  because  Mr.  Field  takes  the  transcendent- 
alist  point  of  view  here,  and  credits  empiricists  with  taking 
it  also,  that  any  such  apparent  difficulty  arises.  If  Tom 
Smith  who,  for  the  empirical  psychologist,  is  the  sum  total 
of  processes  occurring  in  awareness,  be  completed  empirically 
by  the  sum  total  of  ''unconscious"  processes  which,  simi- 
larly, are  John  Jones,  the  addition  of  the  two  will  not 
constitute  two  "persons,"  but  one  complete  phenomenal 


432  F.   AVELING: 

consciousness — Thomas  John  Jones-Smith.  Indeed,  there 
would  not  be  even  one  "  person  "  so  constituted  ;  for  it  could 
hardly  be  asserted  that  a  phenomenal  consciousness,  no 
matter  how  complete,  was  a  "  person  ".  But  this  conception 
has,  none  the  less,  the  advantage  of  remaining  within  (at 
least  theoretically  possible)  empirical  limits,  and  of  providing 
a  ground  for  the  establishing  of  scientific  concomitances  and 
sequences,  without  the  necessity  of  having  recourse  to  meta- 
physical notions. 

I  do  not  wish  it  to  be  understood  that  I  in  any  way  imply 
a  denial  that  metaphysical  conceptions  may  be  necessary  for 
a  final  explanation  of  the  facts.  Mental  structure  and  ten- 
dencies, brain  and  body — or,  better  perhaps,  the  substantial 
individual  which  we  call  "  man  " — may,  in  the  last  resort, 
be  the  only  principle  by  which  the  occurrence  of  experience, 
or  awareness,  can  be  accounted  for  at  all.  I  believe  that  to 
be  so  ;  that  psychology,  like  any  other  science,  must  be  com- 
pleted by  philosophy ;  and  that  its  data  must  be  ultimately 
interpreted  by  means  of  metaphysical  concepts.  But  I  also 
hold  that  it  is,  or  can  be  treated  as,  a  science.  And,  in  that 
aspect,  it  would  appear  that  a  good  case  can  be  made  out 
for  the  conception  of  the  Unconscious. 

In  the  course  of  the  present  paper  I  have  made  use  of 
spatial  metaphors,  and  therefore  have  come  under  the  con- 
demnation of  Mr.  Field  that  there  is  clearly  something 
wrong  with  my  conception  of  the  mental.  My  plea  must  be 
that  the  metaphors  in  question  are  convenient  ones ;  that 
analogies  are  not  out  of  place  in  treating  a  matter  of  this 
kind;  and  that  " levels,"  "regions,"  etc.,  are  given  within 
experience — else  there  could  be  no  awareness  of  them  at  all. 
Moreover  I  have  not  used  them  with  a  spatial  implication. 
They  are  metaphors.  In  a  similar  (though  again  not,  of 
course,  in  a  spatial  way)  Mr.  Field  himself  uses  the  meta- 
physical conception  of  "activity"  to  justify  his  conception 
of  "  mental  structure,"  as  expressing  itself  in  a  particular 
kind  of  activity.  That  also  seems  to  be  a  metaphorical  use 
of  the  term ;  and  it,  too,  would  be  impossible  unless  some 
such  thing  as  the  "  consciousness  of  action  "  were  given  in 
experience. 

I  am  also  conscious  of  the  fact  that,  in  drawing  the  dis- 
tinction between  the  potential  and  the  actual,  I  may  be  met 
with  the  objection  that  I  am  going  beyond  the  data  of  ex- 
perience, and  attempting  to  solve  a  difficulty  as  a  realist 
might  attempt  to  solve  the  difficulty  of  the  problem  which 
arises  as  between  things  and  things  known.  But  I  do  not 
consider  that  to  be  a  serious  objection. 


VALUE   OF  THE   UNCONSCIOUS   IN  PSYCHOLOGY  433 

I  ain  suggesting  throughout  that  the  Unconscious  is  a 
useful  conception  in  the  science  of  psychology.  To  do  this 
I  have  endeavoured  to  point  out  that  something  must  be 
supposed  in  the  place  of  processes  which  do  not  occur  in 
awareness  to  explain  what  sometimes  (indeed  generally)  does 
happen  in  awareness.  I  have  underlined  the  conception  of 
psychology  as  an  empirical  science,  and  pointed  out  that  it 
must  be  governed  by  the  method  that  is  imposed  upon 
sciences  which  profess  to  be  empirical.  I  have  put  forward 
instances  to  explain  why  the  Unconscious  is  postulated  as  a 
conception  to  complete  the  science  of  psychology  without 
doing  violence  to  its  method.  And  I  believe  that  the  evi- 
dence which  I  have  submitted  is  sufficient  to  justify  the  con- 
ception as  both  legitimate  and  of  value  in  that  sense  in  which 
it  may  be  applied  to,  and  used  as  explicative  of,  the  observed 
facts. 


III.  BY  JOHN  LAIKD. 

AT  this  time  of  day,  and  with  present  fashions  what  they 
are,  it  may  seem  absurd  even  to  raise  the  question  of  our 
symposium.  The  triumphs  of  the  New  Psychology — as 
exciting,  we  are  told,  as  The  Origin  of  Species — may  seem 
to  have  answered  it  beyond  all  cavil,  so  that  objections  are 
futile  and  doubts  cttmodt. 

This  view,  I  believe,  is  profoundly  misleading.  The  new 
psychologists,  to  be  sure,  assume  the  existence  of  the  un- 
conscious, both  as  a  storehouse  and  as  a  factory ;  they  profess 
to  discover  significant  and  thrilling  contrasts  between  its 
more  accessible  and  its  darker  regions — all  of  which  is,  some- 
how, vastly  important.  This,  however,  does  not  prove  that 
the  unconscious  is  a  valuable  conception.  Properly  speaking, 
indeed,  it  may  not  be  a  conception  at  all.  Is  it  intelligible? 
Is  it  regulative  ?  Does  it  compel  any  specific  deductions  ? 
Does  the  evidence  imply  it  logically  ?  So  far  as  I  can  see, 
the  new  psychologists  need  not  answer  -any  one  of  these 
questions  in  the  affirmative,  and  their  discussions  of  all  of 
them  are  either  perfunctory  or  non-existent.  Fundamentally, 
this  notion,  such  as  it  is,  seems  to  be  only  permissive  in  use. 
The  new  psychologists  need  to  assume  something  retentive 
and  capable  of  various  developments ;  something,  moreover, 
which,  quite  plainly,  is  not  conscious  and  yet  seems  to  play 
an  important  (and  perhaps  a  dominant)  part  in  our  mental 
history.  This  they  call  the  '  unconscious,'  and  we  need  not 

28 


434  JOHN  LAIRD  : 

quarrel  with  them  for  doing  so  ;  but  there  is  a  case  for 
dispute,  surely,  if  this  negative  name  is  used  to  conceal  and 
not  to  assert  our  ignorance,  if  this  permissive  thing  is  pro- 
claimed to  be  a  key-conception,  if  this  nest  of  problems  is 
taken  to  be  a  squadron  of  solutions  to  them,  and  if  positive 
properties  are  assigned  to  an  enigmatic  somewhat  for  no 
better  reason  than  simple  light-heartedness. 

If  this  be  so,  it  is  plain  that  the  subject  of  our  symposium 
really  is  important — and  important  for  reasons  that  have  no 
peculiar  connexion  with  metaphysics.  In  its  permissive  sense, 
the  unconscious  is  not  even  a  working  hypothesis.  It  is  only 
a  proclamation  that  the  work  is  to  go  On  irrespective  of 
certain  theoretical  difficulties  ;  but  if  it  were  a  working  hy- 
pothesis, it  would  still  be  the  duty  of  empirical  psychologists 
to  examine  it  with  the  utmost  rigour.  The  approach  to  the 
sciences  is  decked  with  bright  ideas,  but  there  is  no  science 
until  these  ideas  are  put  to  the  proof.  The  evolution  of 
species,  say,  or  the  transmutation  of  the  elements  had  to  be 
thought  out  in  order  to  become  something  more  than  an 
attractive  and  stimulating  notion,  and  it  would  be  foolish 
of  us  to  expect  that  the  growth  and  the  sublimations  of  the 
'  unconscious '  will  reveal  themselves,  in  a  fury  of  infantile 
'exhibitionism,'  to  more  impatient  eyes. 

Our  problem,  of  course,  is  not  the  value  of  the  New  Psy- 
chology, but  the  specific  value  of  the  New  Unconscious ; 
and  although  explanation  would  be  needed,  it  would  be  quite 
consistent  to  hold  that  the  former  is  epoch-making  and  the 
latter  pernicious.  Keeping  to  the  latter,  then,  we  have  to 
ask  whether  any  intelligible  notion  of  the  unconscious  can 
be  put  forward,  and,  if  so,  what.  I  can  make  nothing  of 
Mr.  Aveling's  '  experiential '  somewhat,  of  which  we  may 
also  have  been  aware,  which  responds  so  amiably  when  we 
'  link  it  up,'  but  fails  to  recognise  the  difference  between 
being  an  experience  and  having  been  one.  Therefore,  with 
regret,  I  turn  to  other  theories,  and  apart  from  vague  and 
irrelevant  references  to  Leibniz's  petites  perceptions  and  the 
like,  I  find  that  the  favourite  account  of  the  unconscious  is 
the  one  which  Mr.  Field  has  quoted  from  Dr.  Jones.  Thus 
Bleuler x  states  that  he  '  understands  by  the  unconscious  all 
those  operations  which  are  in  every  respect  similar  to  the 
ordinary  psychic  ones  with  the  exception  that  they  cannot 
become  conscious ' ;  and  many  of  the  others  say  the  same 
thing. 

This  definition  really  is  preposterous.     It  is  just  like  Mr. 

1  Quoted  by  Varendonck,  The  Psychology  of  Day-Dreams,  p.  19. 


VALUE   OF  THE   UNCONSCIOUS   IN   PSYCHOLOGY.          435 

Churchill's  '  cannibals  in  all  respects  except  the  act  of  de- 
vouring the  flesh  of  the  victims'.  It  is  worse  than  epi- 
phenomenalism.  As  we  all  know,  our  consciousness  is  only 
a  part  of  a  complicated  pattern  of  processes,  very  imperfectly 
known,  although  known  to  have  some  connexion  with  the 
cortex  and,  in  certain  cases,  to  have  more  specific  connexions 
with  definite  cortical  areas  and  with  the  optic  thalamus.  5  It 
is  therefore  a  permissible,  although  a  rash  and  improbable 
view  that  consciousness  is  only  the  upholstery  of  this  self- 
moving  machine,  and  that  the  combustion  engine  is  outside 
consciousness  altogether,  but  it  is  not  at  all  permissible  to 
contend  that  there  is  really  no  difference  in  the  case.  What 
in  the  world  would  consciousness  be  if  it  had  no  shreds  of 
character  of  its  own?  And  is  there  anything  in  nature 
which,  so  to  speak,  is  pure  character,  although  devoid  of 
distinctive  character,  wholly  bereft  of  power,  and  incapable 
even  of  indicating  that  it  has  some  peculiar  properties  and 
effects  of  its  own  ?  Surely  there  is  irony  in  the  thought 
that  this  grotesque  resurrection  should  follow  the  obsequies 
of  epiphenomenalism  so  promptly  and  so  confidently — irony 
and  something  more. 

I  should  like  to  call  attention,  too,  to  another  remarkable 
circumstance  in  the  present  affair,  and  I  shall  try  to  eluci- 
date it  by  referring  again  to  Dr.  Jones.  A  propos  of  Freud's 
'metapsychology,'  this  author,  after  referring  to  Freud's 
'  convincing  logic '  in  support  of  the  unconscious,  proceeds 
to  say  that  Freud  also  raises  '  the  difficult  question  of  the 
precise  difference  between  an  unconscious  idea  and  a  conscious 
one,  and  what  happens  when  the  former  is  converted  into 
the  latter'.1  What  puzzles  me  is  the  state  of  mind  of  anyone 
who  does  not  see  that  this  '  difficult '  question  is  the  same 
question  precisely  as  the  easy  one.  An  '  unconscious  '  that 
has  not  made  up  its  mind  about  the  '  difficult '  question  is 
simply  a  pattern  in  ink,  and  our  problem,  as  I  understand 
it,  is,  quite  precisely,  whether  any  sort  of  intelligible  answer 
could  be  given  to  this  single  question — whether  it  be  easy 
or  whether  it  be  difficult. 

Some  of  the  difficulties  in  the  case,  I  think,  may  be  easily 
exaggerated.  One  might  try  to  score  a  debating  point,  for 
example,  by  pointing  out  that  although  the  similarity  between 
the  conscious  and  the  unconscious  is  the  burden  of  these 
definitions,  the  difference  between  the  two  is  commonly 
taken  to  be  the  most  important  result  of  the  New  Research. 
This  apparent  contradiction,  however,  is  less  formidable  than 

1  British  Journal  of  Psychology  (Medical  Section)  Vol.  i.,  Pt.  i.,  p.  65. 


436  JOHN  LAIED: 

it  seems.  It  is  only  opposites  of  the  same  kind  that  can, 
properly  speaking,  be  contrasted.  We  contrast  red  with 
green,  not  with  the  multiplication  table.  And  although  the 
point  needs  clearing  up,  especially  in  view  of  the  numerous 
psycho-analytic  '  explanations '  which  make  the  unconscious, 
reputed  a-logical,  behave  (on  occasion)  in  a  thoroughly 
reasonable  manner,  it  need  not  involve  a  flat  contradiction. 

Again,  there  is  no  demonstrable  contradiction  in  the  general 
term  '  unconscious  mind '  if  this  term  means  simply  '  that  in 
the  mind  which  is  de  facto  unconscious '.  No  doubt  it  is 
easy  to  manufacture  hopeless  difficulties  of  this  kind  (as 
Mr.  Aveling  does  when  he  says  that  the  unconscious  must 
be  '  mental  or  "  conscious  "  '),  but  usually,  when  we  speak  of 
a  mind,  we  ascribe  dispositions,  tendencies,  potentialities,  and 
capacities  to  it.  These  are  dangerous  terms,  to  be  sure,  but 
they  are  not  unmeaning,  and  the  facts  they  purport  to  de- 
scribe are  seldom,  if  ever,  conscious  facts.  On  the  other 
hand,  the  New  Unconscious,  so  far  as  I  can  see,  has  neither 
elucidated  these  conceptions,  nor  added  to  them  on  any  point 
of  principle.  The  New  Psychology,  we  may  concede,  has 
shown  that  we  have  many  tendencies  which  were  hitherto 
unsuspected  or  ignored,  and  that  many  of  our  dispositions 
have  sinuous,  sinister,  and  surprising  effects.  But  this  is 
another  story,  however  important  it  may  be.  The  results 
of  the  new  psychology  would  neither  be  altered  nor  gainsaid 
if  the  new  unconscious  were  in  fact  physiological,  or  even  if 
consciousness  itself  were  ultimately  a  quality  that  our  nerves 
can  sometimes  assume. 

In  saying  that  terms  like  capacities  or  dispositions  are  not 
unmeaning,  I  do  not  wish  to  assert  that  they  are  indispensable 
from  every  point  of  view.  If,  for  example,  the  concept  of 
'  mnemic  causation '  could  be  accepted  and  it  were  agreed 
that  a  remote  event  might  be  the  immediate  antecedent  of 
a  present  process,  much  that  is  plausible  in  these  concepts 
would  cease  to  be  so.  The  need  for  '  traces '  would  disappear, 
and  the  ripening  and  developing  of  these  dispositions  would 
be  the  only  circumstance  that  required  attention.  In  view 
of  what  we  learn  about  time  from  modern  physics  it  would 
be  rash  to  flout  this  possibility ;  but  if  we  assume,  with 
common  sense,  that  an  idea  which  has  been  followed  by 
other  ideas  cannot  have  any  direct  influence  after  the  interim, 
we  are  forced  to  assume  some  sort  of  continuing  disposition 
in  order  to  bridge  the  gap.  On  the  other  hand,  we  simply 
do  not  know  what  this  disposition  is  either  in  ordinary 
'  foreconscious '  memory  or,  let  us  say,  in  Dr.  Rivers's  case 
of  claustrophobia,  any  more  than  we  can  say  what  the 


VALUE   OF  THE   UNCONSCIOUS  IN  PSYCHOLOGY.  437 

knavery  of  a  sleeping  rascal  actually  is.  All  that  we  know 
is  that  the  rascal  would  be  a  slippery  customer  under  other 
circumstances. 

It  follows,  however,  that  we  may  speak,  thoroughly  intel- 
ligibly (although  barbarously),  of  unconscious  '  trends '  and 
*  impulsions  '  and  '  urges '  as  well  as  of  unconscious  '  com- 
plexes '  of  these ;  for  these  terms  mean  only  that  there  is 
something  persistent  but  unknown  which  is  capable,  with  or 
without  internal  development  and  rearrangement,  of  forming 
a  specific  bond  of  connexion  between  certain  vanished  ideas 
and  emotions  on  the  one  hand,  and,  on  the  other  hand,  cer- 
tain other  ideas  and  emotions  which  appear  after  an  interim. 
It  may  very  well  happen,  however,  that  there  is  no  intelligible 
meaning  in  speaking  of  unconscious  wishes,  or  desires,  or 
memories,  or  expectations,  or  intentions,  or  emotions,  or  re- 
solves, or  ideas,  and  I  wish  to  consider  this  question  in  some- 
what greater  detail. 

The  theories  of  the  Behaviourists — whom  I  take  to  be  the 
Newest  Psychologists — have  shown  us,  no  doubt,  that  a  cer- 
tain meaning  (perhaps  even  a  certain  precision)  can  be  at- 
tached to  these  terms  provided  we  admit  that  there  is  no 
such  thing  as  consciousness.  This,  however,  is  precisely 
what  many  of  us  cannot  admit  at  all.  We  recognise,,  of 
course,  that  our  consciousness  is  intimately  allied  with  bodily 
reactions,  and  perhaps  that  it  could  not  arise  without  an 
affector  beginning,  or  persist  without  an  effector  continuation ; 
but  we  do  not  and  cannot  admit  that  the  only,  difference  be- 
tween being  awake  and  being  ansesthetised  is  a  difference  in 
bodily  reactions,  or  that  human  happiness  or  human  misery 
would  be  worth  a  moment's  consideration  unless  they  were, 
most  emphatically,  conscious  happiness  and  conscious  misery. 
If  this  be  so — if  consciousness  and  unconsciousness  are,  quite 
certainly,  not  the  same — it  is  quite  impossible,  I  think,  to 
qualify  any  of  the  terms  I  have  mentioned  by  the  adjective 
'  unconscious  '  without  stultifying  ourselves  completely  ;  and 
Behaviourism  does  not  help  us  in  this  particular. 

On  the  other  hand,  there  are  certain  distinctions  within 
consciousness  which  may  seem  to  throw  light  on  the  problem, 
and  these  require  most  careful  scrutiny.  The  chief  of  them, 
I  think,  are  the  distinctions  between  reflective  self-conscious- 
ness and  consciousness  simpliciter,  between  consciousness 
which  is  connected  and  consciousness  which  is  dispersed, 
between  focal  and  marginal  consciousness,  and  between 
schematic  and  detailed  consciousness.  I  shall  examine  these 
distinctions,  then,  in  this  order. 

(1)  There  is  an  idea  abroad,  often  left  unchallenged,  that  a 


438  JOHN  LAIRD: 

man  is  conscious  only  of  that  which  he  avows  to  himself 
upon  reflexion.  This  idea  seems  to  me  simply  false.  For 
the  most  part,  it  is  true,  we  have  a  general,  un examined, 
uninterrogated  notion  of  the  way  our  thoughts  are  drifting, 
but  self-conscious  avowal  or  reflective  self-questioning  is  the 
exception  and  not  the  rule.  It  is  beside  the  point,  therefore, 
to  urge  that  a  man  may  do  shady  things  without  admitting 
to  himself  that  they  are  shady.1  Of  course  he  may,  but  it 
does  not  follow  that  these  actions  were  unconscious.  All 
that  follows  is  that  the  man  did  not  consider  or  did  not  notice 
some  of  their  moral  aspects.  Unselfconscious  thinking, 
similarly,  may  and  does  occur ;  but  it  is  unconscious  conscious- 
ness, not  uns0Z/-conscious  consciousness,  that  is  the  trouble. 
This  distinction,  consequently,  does  not  seem  to  help  us. 

(2)  Each  of  us  knows,  from  the  plainest  experience,  that 
the  course  of  his  thoughts  is  sometimes  tense  and  concen- 
trated, sometimes  rambling,  ambling  and  dispersed.  The 
player's  wits  are  fiercely  preoccupied ;  the  spectator's  thoughts 
may  go  wool-gathering  or  building  castles  in  Spain  ;  and 
drugs  like  scopolamine  (or  mere  sleepy-headedness  for  that 
matter)  turn  all  our  ideas  into  bemused  stragglers.  This, 
however,  is  no  proof  that  the  stragglers  are  unconscious.  It 
proves  only  that  they  are  out  of  the  ranks;  and  if  the 
stragglers,  as  in  the  Beauchamp  case,  sometimes  mass  them- 
selves into  loosely  organised  bands  of  their  own,  this,  in  itself, 
need  not  affect  the  general  principle. 

No  doubt,  if  we  could  show,  as  the  new  psychology  has 
gone  a  long  way  towards  showing,  that  there  are  some  definite 
laws  for  the  stragglers'  wanderings,  our  results  would  be  very 
important,  but  they  need  not  affect  the  question  before  us. 
To  say  that  dispersed  ideas  are  '  split  off '  is  only  to  say  that 
our  thoughts  are  disconnected.  In  this  sense,  and  in  this 
sense  only,  ideas  may  be  '  split  off'  into  groups,  blind  for  the 
time  being  to  one  another's  existence  (as  in  '  alternating 
personalities  '  and  the  like),  and,  of  course,  there  is  no  logical 
contradiction  in  supposing  an  infinity  of  co-conscious  trains 
of  ideas  connected  with  every  living  body,  just  as  there  is  no 
contradiction  in  supposing  an  infinity  of  invisible  auras  round 
every  human  head,  or  an  infinity  of  guardian  angels  sustain- 
ing and  controlling  every  human  life.  These  suggestions, 
however,  leave  the  problem  of  the  '  unconscious '  precisely 
where  it  was.  The  difficulty  about  co-consciousness  is  not 
that  it  is  unthinkable  but  that  the  evidence  for  it  is  lacking. 
We  are  told  that  it  is  there,  and  when  we  go  into  the  ques- 

1  Cf.  Russell,  The  Analysis  of  Mind,  p.  32. 


VALUE   OF   THE   UNCONSCIOUS   IN   PSYCHOLOGY.          439 

tion,  we  find  that  only  one  consciousness  is  in  the  house  at 
any  given  time,  and  that  the  other  must  be  supposed  to  be 
concealed  somewhere  in  the  neighbourhood.  It  will  come  if 
you  *  tap,'  if  you  open  its  coffin,  if  you  make  the  proper 
mesmeric  passes.  Meanwhile,  however,  it  is  not  there 
(although  you  think  it  is  doing  something)  and  when  it  is 
there  you  may  look  in  vain  for  the  other  housemate.1 

This  way  of  speaking,  to  be  sure,  would  be  quite  legitimate 
if  we  were  dealing  with  things  like  Mr.  Aveling's  bullet 
which  remain  the  same  whether  they  are  present  to  our  ex- 
perience or  not.  The  trouble  about  ideas,  and  wishes,  and 
the  like,  however,  is  precisely  that  they  do  not  seem  to  be 
anything  at  all,  except  when  they  are  present  conscious  facts. 
A  dead  body  is  at  least  a  corpse,  but  a  vanished  idea  is  simply 
nothing.  It  was  and  is  not,  just  as  that  glorious  putt  which 
you  made  last  year  was  and  is  not.  To  be  sure,  this  putt  of 
blessed  memory  had  important  after  effects.  You  have  never 
been  the  same  man  since  ;  but  you  need  not  suppose,  surely, 
that  you  have  been  putting  ever  since,  in  your  bed  and  at 
your  meals,  or,  if  not  putting,  then  quasi-putting,  or  putting 
'  minimally,'  in  a  word  unputtingly.  And  although  you  may 
say  that  you  often  miss  your  putts  because  of  the  co-putting 
that  is  going  on  inside  you,  you  need  not  expect  to  convince 
everyone  that  you  are  either  '  scientific  '  or  '  empirical '  when 
you  say  such  things.  Instead  of  that  you  are  a  'meta- 
physician '  of  the  baser  sort,  for  you  are  trafficking  in  occult 
verbiage. 

Therefore,  I  do  not  think  that  this  distinction  between 
concentrated  and  dispersed  proves  what  it  is  supposed  to 
prove. 

(3)  The  distinction  between  the  '  centre '  and  the  '  margin ' 
of  '  consciousness '  is  a  matter  of  empirical  observation,  and 
any  psychologist  who  neglects  the  margin  does  so  without 
excuse.  What  is  more,  the  outskirts  of  this  fringe  are  un- 
doubtedly nebulous  and  impalpable.  It  is  probable,  there- 
fore, that  the  margin  reaches  further  than  we  commonly 
think,  and  certain  that  we  cannot  usually  tell  precisely  where 

1  A  certain  type  of  co-consciousness,  no  doubt,  is  quite  familiar  in 
ordinary  experience,  e.g.,  when,  brushing  my  coat,  I  look  out  for  a  tramway 
car  and  converse  with  a  friend  the  while.  There  is  sufficient  evidence, 
too,  of  a  certain  exaggeration  of  facts  of  this  kind,  in  some  of  Janet's 
hysterical  patients.  This,  however,  does  not  seem  to  me  to  affect  the 
principle  of  what  I  have  said,  and  Dr.  Prince's  specific  attempt  to  prove 
literal  co-consciousness  (i.e.,  two  completely  distinct  mental  series,  con- 
nected with  the  same  body,  both  of  which  are  actually  conscious  at  pre- 
cisely the  same  moment)  seems  to  me  to  be  inconclusive.  (See  The 
Dissociation  of  a  Personality,  pp.  321-322.) 


440  JOHN   LAIED  : 

it  stops.  This  circumstance,  however,  carries  us  but  a  very 
short  way.  If  we  cannot  discern  where  precisely  our  vision 
ends,  we  do  not  conclude,  on  this  account,  that  we  can  see 
with  the  back  of  our  heads.  Indeed  we  know,  in  this  case, 
that  the  margin  does  not  extend  very  far.  Similarly  we 
recognise,  in  this  case,  that  there  is  a  perfectly  definite  and 
inescapable  difference  between  the  things  that  are  about  to 
be  seen,  or  that  we  may  readily  see,  and  the  things  that  we 
actually  do  see,  marginally  or  otherwise.  I  do  not  wish  to 
argue  that  the  penumbra  of  visual  consciousness  is  precisely 
similar  in  all  relevant  respects  to  all  other  conscious 
penumbrse,  but  I  see  no  reason  for  supposing  any  profound 
difference  in  principle,  and  until  some  such  reason  is  shown 
I  shall  continue  to  believe  that  (although  there  may  be 
limited  debatable  regions)  in  general  we  have  quite  sufficient 
reasons  for  asserting  the  absence  of  consciousness  as  well  as 
for  asserting  its  presence,  that  we  have  no  reason  whatever 
for  using  the  '  margin '  as  a  dumping  ground  for  anything 
which  our  theories  may  happen  to  find  convenient,  and  that, 
in  so  far  as  the  '  fore-conscious '  simply  describes  things 
which  we  may  readily  call  to  mind,  it  need  not  be  marginal 
at  all. 

(4)  The  terms  '  marginal '  and  '  schematic'  are  not  equi- 
valent (although  the  margin  is  schematic  and  not  detailed), 
because  the  whole  of  my  consciousness,  both  centre  and 
fringe,  may  be  vague  and  schematic.  Cases  of  this  sort 
abound.  The  novel  which  as  yet  is  but  dimly  foreshadowed 
in  the  intense  inane,  the  mot  juste  which  seems  so  near  to  us 
and  is  yet  so  hard  to  attain,  the  oration  which,  before  it  is 
made,  is  only  a  sort  of  dim  glow  in  our  souls — these  and 
similar  experiences  offer  unmistakable  instances;  and  it  is 
easy  to  misinterpret  them.  No  one  seriously  believes,  I 
fancy,  that  my  schematic  notion,  say,  of  the  Vedanta,  actually 
contains  the  Vedanta,  implicitly  or  otherwise.  Even  to 
suppose  so  would  be  to  suppose  nonsense.  The  Vedanta  is 
not  '  buried '  in  this  grave ;  but  many  seem  to  suppose  that 
if  my  schema  of  a  novel  turns  into  a  novel,  or  my  schema  of 
an  oration  turns  into  an  oration,  then,  somehow  or  other,  the 
novel  or  the  oration  was  unconsciously  present  in  the  schema 
all  the  time ;  and  if  the  schema  seems  to  hover  over  some- 
thing momentarily  forgotten  but  familiar  to  the  feeling, 
nearly  everyone  speaks  of  buried  and  familiar  ideas  struggling 
to  see  the  light  of  conscious  day. 

In  my  view,  the  schema  of  the  familiar  forgotten  thing  no 
more  contains  the  familiar  forgotten  thing,  buried  and 
struggling,  than  my  schema  of  the  Vedanta  contains  the 


VALUE   OF  THE   UNCONSCIOUS   IN   PSYCHOLOGY.          441 

Vedanta,  buried  and  struggling.  The  schema  of  my  oration, 
so  carefully  planned  beforehand,  guides  me  as  I  speak ;  it 
feels  familiar,  perhaps,  and  even  satisfactory ;  it  feels  different 
from  other  schemata  of  other  orations ;  but  it  is  not  the 
oration  itself  and  it  does  not  contain  the  oration.  There  is 
no  oration  until  I  give  it,  no  idea  until  I  think  one,  no  ex- 
pression until  the  expression  comes.  The  schema  (which 
we  may  suppose,  for  simplicity's  sake,  to  be  the  whole  fact 
of  consciousness  when  I  begin  my  oration),  may  prompt  me 
continuously  as  I  go  on  to  explain  myself  in  detail,  and  the 
oration  may  be  a  logical  or  associative  development  from  this 
schematic  nucleus ;  but  this  is  no  proof,  or  even  the  begin- 
nings of  a  proof,  that  these  subsequent  ideas  or  expressions 
literally  possessed  a  previous  existence  of  any  kind.  A 
schematic  idea  is  just  a  vague  glimpse,  and  a  vague  glimpse 
does  not  embrace  details,  metaphorically  or  otherwise. 

These  contrasts  within  consciousness,  therefore,  neither 
compel  us  to  admit  the  '  unconscious '  (or  a  '  buried '  and 
'  concealed '  consciousness)  nor  elucidate  the  manner  in  which 
an  idea,  or  wish,  or  intention  could  be  unconscious  and  still 
be  itself ;  and  I  do  not  think  that  more  helpful  suggestions 
than  these  ones  are  to  be  found.  In  particular,  Mr.  Aveling's 
suggestion  that  feelings  or  emotions  may  persist  a-cognitively 
seems  to  me  quite  useless  and  forlorn.  It  is  simply  a  mistake, 
I  think,  to  use  '  consciousness '  and  '  cognition  '  as  convertible 
terms,  or  to  suppose  that  the  tripartite  division  is  a  division 
of  anything  except  conscious  states ;  and  the  best  psycho- 
logists deny  the  existence  of  blind  strivings  or  sightless  feel- 
ings. These  phrases,  it  is  true,  may  describe  something  but 
they  do  not  describe  conation  or  feeling-tone. 

What  I  have  been  saying,  I  think,  is  not  at  all  'meta- 
physical '.  It  might  be  better  if  it  were,  but  it  is  not ;  and 
the  point  which  I  wish  to  make  in  conclusion,  while  it 
traverses  Mr.  Aveling's  definitions  of  '  psychology,'  implies 
nothing  more  recondite  than  common  sense.  In  speaking 
of  '  consciousness '  and  its  '  margin '  and  so  forth,  I  have 
been  using  current  phrases  which  are  plainly  elliptical ;  and 
my  argument  has  lost  something  of  clearness  on  this  account. 
Strictly  speaking,  of  course,  the  '  margin  of  my  conscious- 
ness '  is  the  *  margin  of  the  field  of  which  I  am  conscious  ' ; 
and  so  in  other  cases.  What  I  remember,  for  example,  is  a 
past  event  of  which  I  am  at  present  conscious ;  what  I  ex- 
pect is  a  future  event  which  I  believe  to  be  about  to  occur  ; 
and  what  I  call  an  '  idea '  describes  a  complex  state  of  affairs 
in  which  a  conscious  process  on  my  part — an  event  in  my 
psychological  history — is  cognitively  related  to  some  other 
event  which  may  have  occurred  or  may  be  about  to  occur  at 


442   JOHN  LAIRD  :  VALUE  OF  UNCONSCIOUS  IN  PSYCHOLOGY. 

an  earlier  or  at  a  later  date  than  this  conscious  process  of 
mine,  and  which  may  or  may  not  be  part  of  my  own  life- 
history. 

Plainly,  then,  the  problem  of  memory  is  not  how  a  past 
event  has  persisted  or  what  a  future  event  is  now,  but  how 
I  can  look  back  at  a  past  event  or  (in  any  way)  look  forward 
to  a  future  one.  This  'looking,'  it  is  clear,  is  not  past  look- 
ing or  future  looking,  but  looking  at  the  past  or  looking  at 
the  future.  It  occurs  just  when  it  does  occur.  It  is  a  flash 
which  does  not  persist,  although,  as  is  usual  in  the  case  of 
flashes,  a  similar  flash  may  recur.  The  past  event  to  which 
we  return  in  memory,  on  the  other  hand,  is  over  and  done 
with  when  we  look  back  at  it ;  and  it  remains  over  and  done 
with  however  frequently  we  look  back  at  it. 

Now  the  process  of  looking,  whether  forwards  or  back- 
wards or  under  our  noses,  is  a  passing  event  and  logically 
similar  to  any  other  passing  event  (say  the  passing  event  of 
walking  or  jumping),  and  although  these  events  have  conse- 
quences for  our  subsequent  history,  it  is  nonsense  to  say 
that  they  persist.  We  learn  to  walk  by  walking  and  to  jump 
by  jumping,  but  no  one  supposes,  on  this  account,  that  in- 
visible processes  of  unwalking  walking  and  of  unjumping 
jumping,  and  of  every  other  action  that  we  learn  to  perform, 
must  continue  without  a  moment's  intermission  in  order  to 
account  for  the  fact  of  learning;  or  that  the  people  who 
learn  to  '  skate  in  summer '  spend  the  whole  of  the  cricket 
season  practising  a  '  buried '  course  of  unpatinating  patina-' 
tions.  Whatever  goes  on,  it  is  not  this,  and  I  should  be 
sorry  for  the  physiologist  who  did  not  try  to  find  out  what 
really  does  go  on.  The  psychologist,  no  doubt,  has  a  harder 
task,  and  he  has  a  much  better  excuse  for  taking  refuge  in 
metaphors,  but  he  ought  not  to  take  metaphors  literally, 
whatever  the  provocation ;  and  although  the  use  of  these 
metaphors  may  not  seriously  affect  a  great  many  of  his  en- 
quiries, there  is  an  ugly  look  about  them  even  when  they 
seem  to  be  harmless.  So  far  as  I  can  see,  unconscious  con- 
sciousness is  in  precisely  the  same  position,  logically,  as 
unthinking  thinking,  or  unwalking  walking,  and  we  have  no 
more  right  to  say  that  wishes  or  ideas  are  unconscious,  or 
that  '  something  of  the  same  nature  '  is  unconscious,  or  that 
'  something  similar  in  all  respects  except  in  the  respect  of 
being  conscious '  is  unconscious  than  we  have  for  asserting 
that  walking  goes  on  when  we  do  not  walk,  or  that  '  some- 
thing of  the  same  nature '  goes  on,  or  that  '  something  goes 
on  which  is  identical  with  walking  in  all  respects  except  in 
being  pedestrian '. 

It  is  worth  our  while,  I  think,  to  remember  this. 


III.— ARE  HISTORY  AND  SCIENCE  DIFFERENT 
KINDS  OF  KNOWLEDGE?1 

A  SYMPOSIUM  BY  B.  G.  COLLINGWOOD,  A.  E.  TAYLOK, 

AND   R    C.    S.    SCHILLEE. 

I.  BY  K.  G.  COLLINGWOOD. 

FEOM  the  point  of  view  of  the  theory  of  knowledge  or  logic, 
must  a  distinction  be  drawn  between  two  kinds  of  knowledge 
called  respectively  History  and  Science  ? 

Such  a  distinction  is  usually  made :  we  shall  argue  that  it 
is  illusory.  It  is  implicit 2  in  the  whole  drift  of  the  Platonic 
philosophy,  though  Plato  nowhere,  I  think,  states  it  clearly. 
But  Aristotle  not  only  states  it,  but  states  it  in  a  way  which, 
though  only  incidental,  implies  that  it  is  familiar.  In  a  well- 
known  passage  of  the  Poetics  he  remarks  that  poetry  is  more 
scientific3  than  history,  because  poetry  deals  with  the  uni- 
versal, for  instance,  what  a  generalised  type  of  man  would 
do  on  a  generalised  type  of  occasion  (and  this,  he  implies,  as 
knowledge  of  the  universal,  is  science) ,  whereas  history  deals 
with  particular  facts  such  as  what,  on  a  particular  occasion, 
a  particular  person  said.  History  is  thus  the  knowledge  of 
the  particular. 

I.  The  distinction  between  history  as  knowledge  of  the 
particular  and  science  as  knowledge  of  the  universal  has 
become  common  property  and  is  in  general  accepted  without 
question.  We  propose  to  criticise  it :  and  as  a  preliminary, 
we  shall  indicate  two  difficulties  which  we  shall  not  follow 
up. 

1  Contributed  to  the  Joint  Session  of  the  Mind  Association  and  the 
Aristotelian  Society  at  Manchester,  July  14th-16th,  1922. 

2 1  would  suggest,  for  instance,  that  just  so  far  as  Mr.  H  J.  Paton 
(Proc.  Arist.  Soc.,  1922,  pp.  69  seqq.)  is  right  in  identifying  eiVacrta  in 
Plato  with  art,  so  far  TTIO-TIS  is  to  be  identified  with  history,  as  cognition 
of  the  actual,  but  only  yiyvopevov,  individual. 

3<£iXoo-o<£o>repoi>.  I  need  hardly  remind  the  reader  that  what  we  call 
science  Aristotle  regularly  calls  <£tXoo-o<£ia,  a  usage  long  followed  in  this- 
country  and  criticised  rather  spitefully  by  Hegel.  What  we  nowadays 
(having  given  in  to  Hegel)  call  philosophy  Aristotle  calls  <ro$ia, 
or 


444     R.  G.  COLLINGWOOD:  AEE  HISTORY  AND  SCIENCE 

(a)  It  implies  a  metaphysical  distinction  between  two  kinds 
of  entity,  a  particular  and  a  universal,  such  that  any  cognition 
may  be  knowledge  of  the  one  in  isolation  from  the  other. 
This  dualism  is  precisely  the  doctrine  which  Plato  attacked 
in  the  Parmenides  when  he  pointed  out  that  the  universal, 
thus  distinguished  from  the  particular  as  a  separate  object, 
loses  just  its  universality  and  becomes  merely  another  par- 
ticular.    The  mediaeval  nominalists  attacked  it  again,  in  the 
form  in  which  the  realists  held  it :  and  Berkeley  once  more 
attacked  it  in  the  doctrine  of  abstract  ideas.     Any  one  of 
these   three   arguments  could   be   directed  with   disastrous 
effect  on  the  metaphysical  groundwork  of  the  distinction 
between  history  and  science  :   but  we  shall  not  undertake 
this   task   because   the   arguments  in   question   are   purely 
destructive,  and   like  all   destructive   arguments   would   be 
waved  aside  as  mere  examples  of  the  *  difficulties '  which 
seem  only  to  stimulate  the  faith  of  the  believer. 

(b)  We  might  drop  metaphysics  and  appeal  to  experience, 
which  clearly  enough  shows  the  instability  of  such  a  dualism. 
Wherever  people  have  distinguished  science  and  history  as 
different  kinds  of  knowledge  they  have  tended  to  degrade 
one  into  the  position  of  a  pseudo-knowledge  and  to  erect  the 
other  into  the  only  real  knowledge. 

(i)  In  Greek  thought  science  or  knowledge  of  the  universal 
is  real  knowledge  and  history  or  knowledge  of  the  particular 
is  only  half-knowledge.  For  Plato  the  particular  is  midway 
hetween  being  and  not-being,  and  therefore  our  best  possible 
cognitions  of  it  are  midway  between  knowledge  and  igno- 
rance. They  are  not  knowledge :  they  are  mere  opinion. 
For  Aristotle  the  qualification  of  poetry  as  more  scientific 
than  history  implies  that  poetry  (and  therefore  a  fortiori 
science)  comes  nearer  to  satisfying  the  ideal  of  knowledge 
than  history  does.  This  position  became  traditional,  and 
crops  out  in  a  curious  way  in  the  nineteenth  century.  It 
was  common  in  that  period  to  propose  that  history  should 
be  elevated  to  the  rank  of  a  science :  which  meant  that  it 
had  hitherto  not  been  a  science  because  it  only  recognised 
the  particular,  but  that  now  this  reproach  was  to  be  removed, 
and  after  a  long  apprenticeship  spent  in  the  proper  Baconian 
way  in  collecting  facts  history  was  to  be  promoted  to  the 
task  of  framing  general  laws,  and  thereby  converted  into  a 
science  fit  to  take  its  place  among  the  other  sciences  like 
•chemistry  and  mechanics.  This  proposal,  to  redeem  history 
from  its  degraded  infra-scientific  position,  became  part  of  the 
regular  programme  of  nineteenth-century  empiricism  and 
positivism,  and  the  science  into  which  it  was  to  be  converted 


DIFFERENT   KINDS   OF   KNOWLEDGE?  445 

was  variously  entitled  Anthropology,  Economics,  Political  or 
Social  Science,  the  Philosophy  of  History,  and  Sociology. 

(ii)  The  opposite  tendency  has  been  late  in  appearing,  but 
it  has  made  amends  for  its  lateness.  The  chief  feature  of 
European  philosophy  in  the  last  generation  has  been  that 
movement  of  reaction  from  nineteenth-century  positivism 
which  has  tended  to  degrade  science  into  a  false  form  of 
knowledge  and  to  find  the  true  form  in  history.  The  meta- 
physical notion  of  reality  as  process,  movement,  change,  or 
becoming  has  had  its  reverse  (perhaps  really  its  obverse)  side 
in  an  epistemology  which  places  history  at  the  centre  of 
knowledge.  In  this,  implicitly  if  not  explicitly,  the  schools 
of  Mach,  of  Bergson,  of  James,  and  of  Croce  agree :  and 
even  more  plainly  they  agree  in  holding  that  science  is  not 
knowledge  at  all  but  action,  not  true  but  useful,  an  object  of 
discussion  not  to  epistemology  but  to  ethics.  Any  cognition 
(such  seems  to  be  the  Berkeleian  principle  common  to  these 
schools)  must  be  of  the  particular,  and  must  therefore  be 
history :  what  is  called  a  cognition  of  the  universal  cannot 
be  a  cognition  at  all  but  must  be  an  action.  They  do  not 
all  intend  by  this  analysis  to  '  degrade '  science  in  the  sense 
of  denying  its  value :  for  it  is,  they  maintain,  useful :  what 
they  deny  is  simply  its  truth. 

Experience  shows  the  difficulty  of  keeping  the  balance 
even  and  the  temptation  to  identify  the  genus  knowledge 
with  one  of  its  species,  thereby  reducing  the  other  to  the 
position  of  an  expedient  towards  knowledge  or  an  inferior 
kind  of  knowledge.  But  no  one  who  really  wishes  to  main- 
tain the  dualism  will  let  this  deter  him.  Grant  that  every  one 
from  Plato  to  Croce  has  failed  to  maintain  it,  lie  will  not  fail 
but  will  stand  by  the  very  simple  doctrine  that  knowledge 
is  a  genus  with  two  species  :  knowledge  of  the  particular, 
history,  and  knowledge  of  the  universal,  science.  This 
simple  faith  in  the  possibility  of  maintaining  a  dualism  by 
sheer  will-power,  undeterred  by  the  spectacle  of  the  bleaching 
bones  of  previous  adventurers,  is  left  untouched  by  the  ex- 
pressions of  a  disillusioned  scepticism.  We  shall  not  pursue 
this  line  of  criticism,  but  shall  try  simply  to  describe  how 
the  scientist  and  the  historian  work,  in  order  to  see  whether 
we  can  detect  a  fundamental  difference  between  them. 

II.  It  is  commonly  assumed  that  what  the  scientist  does, 
in  virtue  of  which  he  is  a  scientist,  is  to  generalise.  Every- 
thing else  which  he  may  do,  it  is  thought,  is  (in  so  far  as  he 
is  a  scientist)  a  means  to  this  end.  When  it  is  achieved  his 
work  is  done  and  there  is  nothing  more  for  him  to  do  ex- 
cept to  go  on  and  frame  a  new  generalisation.  That  is  the 


446      E.   G.    COLLINGWOOD  :    AEE   HISTORY  AND   SCIENCE 

meaning  of  the  common  saying  that  science  is  the  know- 
ledge of  the  universal.  Is  it  true  ? 

As  a  common  opinion  it  may  be  countered  with  another. 
Generalisations  can  be  learnt  by  hearsay  or  reading :  for 
instance,  you  may  learn  by  heart  the  list  of  fossils  character- 
istic of  a  certain  horizon  by  simply  getting  them  up  from  a 
book.  Now  common  opinion  holds  that  a  man  may  be 
book-learned  in  a  science  and  yet  incompetent  in  it.  A 
geologist  may  know  the  names  of  fossils,  but  if  we  find  on 
putting  him  down  in  front  of  an  actual  landscape  or  in  an 
actual  quarry  that  he  cannot  give  us  a  geological  account  of 
this  particular  object,  we  say  that  he  is  an  impostor.  He 
can  repeat,  it  may  be,  all  the  generalisations  which  (we 
generally  think)  constitute  the  corpus  of  geological  science, 
but  if  he  cannot  apply  them  he  is  no  geologist. 

Friends  and  enemies  of  the  natural  sciences  agree  in 
thinking  the  application  of  generalisations  to  be  characteristic 
of  them,  and  so  it  is,  but  not  in  quite  the  way  that  is 
generally  thought.  '  Science '  is  praised  or  despised  for  its 
practical  or  economic  value,  and  the  geologist  is  respected 
or  scorned  for  being  able  to  tell  us  where  to  look  for  coal. 
It  is  implied  that  geology  means  not  merely  knowing  gener- 
alities but  interpreting  particular  facts  in  the  light  of  these 
generalities  :  being  able  to  say  *  my  geological  learning  leads 
me  to  believe  that  there  is  coal  just  below  this  sandstone '. 
And  it  is  implied  that  the  person  who  says  this  is  more 
entitled  to  the  name  of  geologist  than  one  who  just  reels  off 
general  statements. 

The  common  view  of  science  as  essentially  useful  or 
utilitarian  is  not  wholly  erroneous ;  it  conceals  an  important 
truth,  namely  that  a,  scientist  is  only  a  scientist  evepyeia  when 
he  is  interpreting  concrete  facts  in  the  light  of  his  general  con- 
cepts, and  that  the  framing  of  these  concepts,  if  regarded  as 
something  distinct  from  the  application  of  them,  is  not  the 
end  of  science  but  the  means.  The  geologist  evepyeia  is  the 
man  who  is  occupied  not  in  repeating,  nor  even  in  inferring, 
generalised  truths,  but  in  looking  at  country  with  a  geologist's 
eye,  understanding  it  geologically  as  he  looks  at  it,  or 
'  applying '  his  geological  concepts  to  the  interpretation  of 
what  he  sees.  To  possess  these  concepts  without  so  applying 
them  is  not  (as  the  view  which  identifies  science  with 
generalisation  would  imply)  to  be  an  actual  geologist,  but 
only  at  most  to  be  a  potential  geologist,  to  possess  the  tools 
of  a  geologist  without  using  them.  But  we  are  here  in 
danger  of  a  serious  mistake.  The  potential  geologist  is  only 
a  mythological  abstraction  :  he  cannot  really  exist :  for  where 


DIFFERENT  KINDS   OF   KNOWLEDGE?  447 

the  '  tool '  is  a  concept  and  the  '  use '  of  it  is  the  interpretation 
of  individual  fact  by  its  means,  the  tool  cannot  be  possessed 
in  idleness.  That  would  be  to  strain  the  metaphor.  Inter- 
pretation is  not  the  employment  of  a  previously-constructed 
tool  (concept)  upon  a  separately-given  material  (fact) :  neither 
the  concept  nor  the  fact  is  '  possessed '  (thought  and  observed 
respectively)  except  in  the  presence  of  the  other.  To  possess 
or  think  a  concept  is  to  interpret  a  fact  in  terms  of  it :  to 
possess  or  observe  a  fact  is  to  interpret  it  in  terms  of  a  con- 
cept. 

Science  is  this  interpretation.  To  live  the  life  of  a  scientist 
consists  in  the  understanding  of  the  world  around  one  in 
terms  of  one's  science.  To  be  a  geologist  is  to  look  at  land- 
scape geologically  :  to  be  a  physiologist  is  to  look  at  organ- 
isms physiologically,  and  so  on.  The  object  which  the 
scientist  cognises  is  not  '  a  universal,'  but  always  particular 
fact,  a  fact  which  but  for  the  existence  of  his  generalising 
activity  would  be  blank  meaningless  sense-data.  His  activity 
as  a  scientist  may  be  described  alternatively  as  the  under- 
standing of  sense-data  by  concepts,  or  the  realising  of  con- 
cepts in  sensation,  '  intuiting  '  his  thoughts  or  '  thinking  out ' 
his  intuitions.  In  this  process  he  recognises  the  objects  be- 
fore him  as  being  of  this  or  that  kind  :  and  sometimes  this 
recognition  results  in  the  discovery  that  they  are  economic- 
ally valuable,  that  is,  it  serves  as  a  basis  for  action.  That 
is  the  truth  which  underlies  the  idea  of  science  as  essentially 
utilitarian :  but  if  we  are  to  use  technicalities  we  shall  say 
that  utility  is  not  its  essence  but  its  accident,  or  at  most  its 
property,  since  ability  to  use  one's  world  perhaps  follows 
necessarily  from  understanding  it.  And  every  science  has 
the  same  character  :  not  only  geology  and  physiology  but  even 
what  we  are  accustomed  to  consider  the  most  abstract 
sciences.  Thus,  to  be  a  chemist  consists  not  in  knowing 
general  formulae  but  in  interpreting  particular  changes  which 
we  observe  taking  place  by  means  of  these  formulae :  the 
science  of  mechanics  consists  in  the  similar  interpretation  of 
observed  motions :  even  mathematics  does  not  consist  of 
abstract  equations  and  formulae  but  in  the  application  of  these 
to  the  interpretation  of  our  own  mathematical  operations. 

A  distinction  is  often  made  between  the  particular  and  the 
individual,  the  former  as  a  mere  abstraction,  the  latter  as 
the  concrete  fact,  synthesis  of  two  opposite  abstractions,  the 
particular  and  the  universal.  If  we  must  conform  to  this 
usage  we  shall  put  our  contention  by  saying  that  there  is 
no  such  thing  as  knowledge  either  of  the  particular  or  of 
the  universal,  but  only  of  the  individual :  and  that  the 


448      E.   G.    COLLINGWOOD  :    ABE   HISTOEY  AND   SCIENCE 

sense-datum  (pure  particular)  and  concept  (pure  universal) 
are  false  abstractions  when  taken  separately  which  yet,  as 
elements  in  the  one  concrete  object  of  knowledge,  the  indi- 
vidual interpreted  fact,  are  capable  of  being  analytically 
distinguished.  This  may  be  illustrated  by  the  fallacy  of 
inductive  logic.  The  inductive  logician  assumes  that  the 
task  of  science  is  to  generalise,  to  frame  universal  laws  ;  and 
that  its  starting-point  is  the  facts  of  ordinary  observation. 
The  problem  of  inductive  logic  then  is  how,  from  the  par- 
ticular facts,  do  we  reach  the  universal  law?  It  tries  to 
describe  this  process  in  detail :  but  when  it  has  done  so  one 
cannot  help  seeing  that  the  alleged  particular  from  which  it 
started  was  never  a  pure  particular  but  was  already  steeped 
in  generality.  The  process  ought  to  have  begun  with  the 
pure  uninterpreted  sense-datum.  It  never  does  so  begin  in 
the  descriptions  of  inductive  logicians,  for  two  excellent 
reasons :  such  a  pure  sense-datum  does  not  exist  except  as 
an  abstraction  and  therefore  cannot  be  the  concrete  starting- 
point  of  a  process,  and  if  it  did  exist  one  could  never  get 
beyond  it  to  reach  the  universal.  So  the  inductive  logician 
makes  the  process  begin  with  the  carefully  staged  experiment 
or  intelligently  recorded  observation,  which  is  not  &  particular 
at  all  but  an  individual,  a  concrete  fact  bristling  with  con- 
ceptual interpretations ;  and  from  this  point,  which  already 
contains  and  presupposes  the  concept,  he  proceeds  to  '  induce  ' 
the  concept  he  has  surreptitiously  presupposed.  How,  after 
this,  he  has  the  face  to  accuse  syllogistic  logic  of  petitio  prin- 
cipii  remains  a  mystery. 

The  scientist's  aim  is,  then,  not  to  '  know  the  universal ' 
but  to  know  the  individual,  to  interpret  intuitions  by  concepts 
or  to  realise  concepts  in  intuitions.  The  reason  why  it  has 
so  often  been  fancied  that  his  aim  is  to  form  generalisations 
is  probably  that  we  expect  science  to  be  contained  in  text- 
books, much  as  we  expect  art  to  be  contained  in  pictures. 
Art  is  to  be  found  not  in  pictures  but  in  our  activity  which 
has  pictures  for  its  object :  and  science  is  to  be  found  in  our 
activity  which  uses  scientific  textbooks,  not  in  the  textbooks 
themselves.  The  teacher  who  puts  a  textbook  into  the 
hands  of  a  student  must  be  understood  as  saying  :  '  I  give 
you  not  science,  but  the  key  to  science  :  the  information  here 
printed  is  not  science,  it  is  something  which  when  you  find 
out  how  to  use  it  will  help  you  to  build  up  in  your  own  mind 
an  activity  which  alone  is  itself  science  '.  It  is  only  because 
this  is  so  obvious  and  so  continually  goes  without  saying  that 
we  habitually  overlook  it. 

III.  The  scientist  generalises,  certainly  :  but  generalisation 


DIFFEEENT  KINDS   OF  KNOWLEDGE?  449 

is  subordinate  to  his  real  work  as  a  scientist,  the  interpreta- 
tion of  individual  fact.  But  the  historian  does  not  remain 
at  a  level  of  thought  below  generalisation  :  he  generalises  too 
and  with  exactly  the  same  kind  of  purpose.  Such  generalisa- 
tions as  charters,  mediaeval  scripts,  types  of  handwriting 
characteristic  of  the  early  fourteenth  century,  guild  institu- 
tions, and  so  forth,  go  to  the  interpretation  of  a  scrap  of 
parchment  which  fits  into  its  place  as  a  link  in  the  history  of 
a  town  precisely  as  fossils,  Jurassic  fauna,  shells  peculiar  to 
the  Portland  beds,  and  so  on,  are  the  concepts  through  which 
a  geologist  works  out  the  geological  history  of  a  valley.  Of 
late,  the  historian's  concepts  have  tended  increasingly  to 
group  themselves  into  what  seem  to  be  independent  sciences, 
palaeography,  numismatics,  archaeology  and  so  forth.  If,  as 
is  mostly  the  case,  they  do  their  work  better  for  being  thus 
incorporated  into  chartered  societies,  well  and  good.  But 
their  work  is  the  interpretation  of  individual  fact,  the  re- 
construction of  historical  narrative  :  and  there  is  a  certain 
danger  that  the  archaeologist,  under  the  influence  of  the  false 
theory  of  science  which  we  have  criticised,  may  forget  this. 
He  may  even  think  that  poor  old  history  has  been  quite 
superseded  by  his  own  science  and  others  like  it,  whose  aim 
is  not  to  individualise  but  to  generalise  :  to  reach  conclusions 
not  in  the  form  '  we  can  now  assert  that  Agricola  built  this 
fort '  but  in  the  form  ( we  can  now  assert  that  Samian  bowls 
of  shape  29  went  out  of  use  about  A.D.  80 '.  The  latter  is 
certainly  the  form  in  which  the  conclusions  of  many  valuable 
monographs  appear  :  but  that  is  just  because  the  monograph 
as  a  whole  is  only  an  incident  in  the  scientific  lives  of  its 
writer  and  readers,  an  incident  whose  importance  lies  in  its 
bearing  on  the  interpretation  of  individual  facts.  Monographs 
are  not  archaeology  :  or  if  they  are,  then  archaeology  is  a  false 
abstraction  and  we  must  say  monographs  are  not  history, 
since  history  is  the  concrete  activity  which  produces  and 
uses  them. 

The  nineteenth-century  positivists  were  right  in  thinking 
that  history  could  and  would  become  more  scientific.  It  did, 
partly  as  a  result  of  their  work,  become  at  once  more  critical 
and  trustworthy,  and  also  more  interested  in  general  con- 
cepts. But  its  interest  in  general  concepts,  reflected  in  the 
rise  of  archaeology  and  such  sciences,  was  the  interest  of  a 
workman  in  the  improvement  of  his  tools.  History  did  not 
subordinate  the  determination  of  facts  to  the  framing  of 
general  laws  based  on  them ;  that  idea  was  part  and 
parcel  of  the  inductive  fallacy.  It  created  within  itself  new 
bodies  of  generalised  thought  subordinated  to  its  own 

29 


450    K.  G.  COLLINGWOOD:   AEE  HISTOKY  AND  SCIENCE 

supreme   end,  the  determination  or  interpretation  of  indi- 
vidual fact. 

IV.  The  analysis  of  science  in  epistemological  terms  is 
thus  identical  with  the  analysis  of  history,  and  the  distinction 
between  them  as  separate  kinds  of  knowledge  is  an  illusion. 
The  reason  for  this  illusion  is  to  be  sought  in  the  history  of 
thought.  The  ancients  developed  a  very  much  higher  type 
of  scientific  than  of  historical  thought :  such  sciences  as 
mathematics,  physics,  logic,  astronomy,  etc.,  in  the  hands  of 
the  Greeks  attained  a  pitch  of  excellence  which  history  did 
not  rival  till  the  seventeenth  century.  Their  philosophical 
reflexions  were  therefore  concentrated  on  scientific  thought 
and  not  on  the  less  remarkable  achievements  of  history :  and 
from  that  time  till  the  nineteenth  century  a  lack  of  balance 
between  the  epistemology  of  science  and  that  of  history  con- 
tinued to  exist.  The  result  was  that  in  the  theory  of  science 
attention  has  always  been  drawn  to  the  concepts  or  principles 
of  interpretation  according  to  which  the  active  work  of 
thought  proceeds,  while  the  theory  of  history  has  contented 
itself  with  attending  to  the  finished  product  of  thought,  the 
fully-compiled  historical  narrative.  This  is  the  root  of  all 
the  alleged  differences  between  history  and  science.  Thus  it 
has  been  said  that  science  predicts,  whereas  history  only 
records  the  past.  That  is  untrue  (geology  records  the  past, 
history  predicts  that  green-glaze  pottery  will  be  found  in  a 
mediaeval  ruin)  except  in  the  sense  that  what  we  arbitrarily 
call  history — the  finished  narrative  when  the  historian  has 
stopped  working  on  it — is  complete  and  immovable,  while 
what  we  arbitrarily  call  science  (the  mere  abstract  generalisa- 
tion) is  an  early  stage  in  the  process  of  thought  which  looks 
forward  to  its  own  completion  in  what  inductive  logic  calls 
verification. 

Again,  it  is  said  that  the  mainspring  of  science  is  critical 
thought,  that  of  history  authority.  That  again  is  wholly 
untrue  unless  we  are  speaking  of  incipient  science  and  com- 
pleted history :  for  every  kind  of  work  is  critical  so  long  as 
the  conclusion  is  not  yet  reached,  and  every  kind  dogmatic 
when  it  is.  A  working  historian  is  critical  in  all  the  same 
ways  as  a  working  scientist,  and  a  scientist  who  has  come  to 
a  conclusion  states  it,  everybody  knows,  as  dogmatically  as 
a  Pope :  it  would  be  a  pedantic  and  insincere  affectation  if 
he  did  not. 

These  and  other  fancied  distinctions  are  the  result  of 
comparing  an  inside  view  of  science  with  an  outside  view  of 
history — science  as  an  actual  process  of  thought  with  history 
as  a  dead,  finished  article.  When  both  are  regarded  as 


DIFFERENT  KINDS  OF  KNOWLEDGE?  451 

actual  inquiries,  the  difference  of  method  and  of  logic  wholly 
disappears.  The  traditional  distinction,  we  have  suggested, 
has  its  origin  in  a  simple  historical  fact,  the  fact  that  science 
became  an  object  of  philosophical  reflexion  long  before  his- 
tory :  not  in  any  epistemological  dualism.  To  erect  such  a 
dualism  is  to  falsify  both  science  and  history  by  mutilating 
each  of  one  essential  element  of  knowledge — the  element  of 
generalisation  or  the  element  of  individualisation  :  and  so 
mutilated,  it  is  not  surprising  if  now  history,  now  science, 
should  appear  an  illegitimate  form  of  knowledge. 


II.    BY  A.  E.  TAYLOR. 

MY  belief  is  that  they  are  different,  and  I  am  now  to  give  a 
brief  statement  of  my  reasons  for  thinking  so.  I  say  my 
reasons  and  no  one  else's,  because  I  do  not  see  that  a  dis- 
cussion of  the  kind  we  are  now  engaged  in  is  likely  to  be 
profitable  if  it  resolves  itself  into  an  attempt  to  count  heads 
and  to  make  out,  largely  by  doubtful  argumentation,  that 
Plato  or  St.  Thomas  or  Hegel  has  taken  sides  and  Eome  has 
therefore  spoken  and  there  is  nothing  left  to  discuss. 

The  view  I  believe  to  be  false  in  principle  can  perhaps  be 
most  readily  indicated,  and  the  reasons  for  thinking  it  false 
most  briefly  suggested,  by  stating  it  in  what  will  perhaps  be 
thought  an  exaggerated  form,  though,  if  the  view  were  only 
true  instead  of  false,  I  do  not  see  that  such  a  statement  would 
be  anything  but  perfectly  appropriate.  Spinoza,  we  all  know, 
undertook  to  write  Ethica  more  geometrico  demonstrata, 
though  most  of  his  readers  have  held  that  the  promise  was 
not  really  redeemed  by  the  performance.  How  if  Gibbon 
had  promised  the  world,  or  if  some  enthusiast  for  the  opinions 
of  the  late  Sir  John  Seeley  were  yet  to  promise  an  Historia 
Imperii  more  geometrico  demonstrata  ?  Should  we,  or  should 
we  not,  expect  to  find  that  in  proportion  as  the  work  was 
good  history,  the  "  geometrical  method  "  eopraefulgebat  quia 
aberat  ?  I  believe  we  should,  and  I  want  to  show  very  suc- 
cinctly why  I  believe  we  should  be  right. 

The  root  of  the  difficulty  does  not  lie,  as  is  often  said,  in 
the  distinction  that  "science  "  deals  with  the  "  universal" 
but  history  with  the  "  individual  ".  This  is,  no  doubt,  true, 
but  if  it  were  all,  a  clever  disputer  could  make  out  a  plausible 
case  for  neglecting  the  distinction  by  arguing  that  the  uni- 
versal truths  of  science  hold  true  of  individual  cases,  and 
that  the  individuals  whose  doings  form  the  subject  of  history 


452         A.  E.  TAYLOR:  ABE  HISTORY  AND  SCIENCE 

are  only  known  to  us  as  objects  with  this  or.  that  complex  of 
" universal"   attributes.     The  real  difficulty  is  rather  that 
science,  when  it  is  "  pure,"  that  is  when  you  have  freed  it 
from  complication  with  any  extraneous  preoccupations,  when 
it  is  all  through  "  science  "  and  nothing  but  "  science,"  never 
affirms  and  never  attempts  to  affirm  anything  but  a  formal 
logical  implication  between  a  proposition  which  it  calls  a 
demonstrated  conclusion  and  a  group  of  other  propositions 
which   it   calls  the  premisses  for   the  conclusion ;  history, 
when  it  is  pure  history,  freed,  to  repeat  myself,  from  all  pre- 
occupation with  the  extraneous,  always  tries  at  least  to  affirm 
the  truth  of  a  categorical  proposition.     Thus,  to  take  a  pair 
of  illustrative  examples,  it  is  no  concern  of  purely  scientific 
science  whether  or  not  the  famous  Pythagorean  proposition 
is  true.     The  scientific  work  is  done  when  it  has  been  shown 
that  a  certain  small  group  of  postulates,  all  explicitly  asserted 
or  tacitly  assumed  without  proof  by  Euclid,  imply  as  a  logi- 
cal consequence  the  theorem  of  Pythagoras,  and  that  if  any 
member  of  this  group  of  postulates  were  omitted  there  would 
be  no  such  implication.     Whether  these  various  postulates 
are  themselves  true  or  not  is  not  a  problem  for  the  geometer 
as  such.     He  may,  so  far  as  I  can  see,  hold  that  they  are 
true,  that,  as  it  is  quaintly  put,  the  "  space  in   which   we 
actually  live"  is  "Euclidean";  he  may  hold  that  some  of 
them  are  not  true,  that  we  "  live  in  a  non-Euclidean  space  "  ; 
he  may  hold  that  one  or  other  of  these  views  is  true  but  that 
we  cannot  tell  which  ;  or  finally,  as  it  seems  to  me — and  I 
could  quote  names,  if  necessary,  to  prove  that  this  is  not 
merely  a  view  of  an  "  outsider"  in  geometry — he  may  think 
that  the  problem  itself  is  on  the  same  level  as  the  question 
whether  the  body  we  call  Jupiter  really  is  Jupiter,  or  whether 
the  true  reckoning  of  money  is  by  pounds  and  shillings,  by 
francs  or  by  dollars.     Our  view  of  his  common  sense  may  be 
affected  by  his  verdict  on  this  issue,  but  not  our  view  of  his 
competence  as  a  geometer.     Or  again,  if  you  start  with  cer- 
tain very  simple  postulates  about  the  type  of  structure  of  the 
integer-series,  you  can,  as  Frege  has  shown  more  elaborately 
than  anyone  else,  deduce  the  whole  system  of  rules  which 
make  up  simple  Arithmetic,  but  it  may  remain  in  doubt  all 
through,  as  Frege  left  it  in  doubt,  whether  there  really  is 
anything  which  answers  to  the  notion  of  an  integer  as  de- 
fined by  your  initial    postulates.     Only  the  doubt  does  not 
in  the  least  affect  what  you  have  really  asserted,  viz.,  that  if 
your  two  or  three  initial  assumptions  are  granted,  the  whole 
bulk  of  your  conclusions  follow  with  strict  logical  necessity. 
You  would  show  yourself  a  bad  "arithmetician"  if  you  de- 


DIFFEKENT   KINDS   OF  KNOWLEDGE?  453 

clared  a  consequence  to  follow  when  it  does  not  follow.  You 
do  not  show  yourself  a  bad  arithmetician  because  it  may  be 
doubtful  whether  one  of  your  postulates  is  true.  All  that  is 
really  demanded  in  regard  to  them  is  that  they  shall  be  as 
few  and  simple  as  possible,  and  that  each  of  them  shall  be 
independent  of  all  the  others,  i.e.,  that  the  consequences 
alleged  to  follow  shall  not  all  follow  if  any  one  of  the  postu- 
lates is  expunged  from  the  list.  Your  crew  must  be  suffi- 
cient to  row  your  boat,  and  it  must  contain  no  "  corkers  ". 

For  the  sake  of  contrast,  take  any  proposition  about  history 
you  please,  the  simpler  and  more  childish  the  better  for  my 
purpose,  e.g.,  "  Eichard  III.  murdered  the  sons  of  Edward 
IV.  in  the  Tower/'  "William  III.  was  an  accessory  to  the 
Rye  House  Plot ".  The  main  point  of  interest  here  to  the 
historian  of  our  country  is  whether  these  allegations  are 
themselves  true  or  not.  If  the  princes  were  still  alive  when 
Henry  VII.  reached  London,  or  if  "Hooknose"  knew 
nothing  about  the  Eye  House  Plot  until  the  arrest  of  the 
real  or  alleged  plotters,  these  statements  are  simply  false 
history.  The  existence  of  a  logical  implication  between  the 
premisses  and  the  conclusions  based  on  them  is  here  only 
interesting  in  a  secondary  way  for  its  bearing  on  the  truth 
of  the  conclusions  themselves.  In  point  of  fact,  the  historian 
only  rarely,  if  ever,  really  succeeds  in  putting  the  logical  im- 
plication beyond  all  doubt.  In  our  own  example,  the  first 
proposition  is  one  which  most  historians  have  accepted,  the 
second  one  which  they  have  rejected.  Yet  the  kind  of  evi- 
dence produced  to  establish  the  connexion  of  premisses  with 
conclusion  appears  to  be  about  as  good  in  one  case  as  in  the 
other  ;  in  both,  as  a  matter  of  logic,  alternative  readings  of 
the  facts  are  really  left  open. 

It  is  not  to  the  point  to  argue  against  this  real  distinction 
by  urging  that  the  individual  persons  and  events  of  history 
have  universal  characters  and  that  it  is  these  characters 
which  make  up  what  we  really  know  about  them.  The 
question  is  what  it  is  we  are  interested  in  establishing  and 
what  we  think  it  our  business  to  establish  in  history.  We 
are  emphatically  not  interested,  when  we  write  the  history 
of  Eichard  III.,  to  make  out  the  proposition  that  a  politician 
with  the  character  we  believe  King  Eichard  to  have  had  is 
very  likely  to  put  rivals  whose  pretensions  may  be  a  source 
of  difficulty  and  danger  out  of  the  way  if  he  has  them  in  his 
power.  We  may  grant  this  implication  quite  freely,  and 
yet,  if  some  one  were  to  produce  undeniable  evidence  of  the 
existence  of  the  two  princes  after  the  battle  of  Bosworth, 
though  the  evidence  might  not  lead  us  to  make  any  alteration 


454  A.    E.   TAYLOE:    AEE   HISTOEY  AND   SCIENCE 

in  our  hypothetical  estimate  of  Richard's  character,  and  so 
would  leave  the  general  implication  still  standing,  we  should 
certainly  feel  that  we  were  in  the  presence  of  a  new  historical 
fact,  and  we  should  feel  called  on  to  rewrite  history  accord- 
ingly. The  plain  fact  is  that  what  the  great  representatives 
of  the  scientific  ideal  have  always  been  interested  in  is  viewing 
things,  as  one  of  the  greatest  wrote,  sub  specie  quadam  aeter- 
nitatis.  They  are  only  interested  in  their  temporal  character 
so  far  as  this  can  be  regarded  as  a  clue  to  their  eternal  char- 
acter; they  may  have  to  allow,  in  some  cases,  for  the 
temporal  in  their  premisses ;  their  aim  is  to  exclude  it,  if 
they  can,  from  their  conclusions,  and  this  is  the  real  reason 
for  the  "  hypothetical-deductive "  method  which  all  science 
does  its  best  to  follow.  But,  thank  God,  all  our  interest  and 
all  our  knowledge  is  not  confined  to  the  species  quaedam 
aeternitatis ;  we  are  also  interested  in  the  temporal  as  tem- 
poral, and  we  can  know  a  great  deal  about  it ;  even  if  you 
decline  to  call  this  knowledge  science,  as  I  think  you  ought, 
it  is  "information,"  and  it  is  just  because  we  care  about 
information  that  there  is  a  substantive  study  of  history.  Of 
course  you  can  make  the  study  merely  subservient  to  that 
other  interest  in  the  non-temporal.  You  can  treat  history 
as  merely  offering  a  starting-point  for  the  framing  of  hypo- 
thesis about  tendencies  in  human  nature.  At  its  best, 
however,  the  result  of  that  kind  of  study  is  not  history  but 
"Politics,"  the  study  of  the  legislator  and  statesman  ;  at  its 
worst,  it  becomes  the  medley  of  crude  guesses  which  has 
dignified  itself  appropriately  enough  by  the  vulgar  and  hybrid 
appellation  of  "  sociology,"  an  unlovely  simia  Politicae.  But 
Politics  and  sociology  are  both  discriminated  from  true 
science  by  the  multitude  of  their  unproved  postulates,  the 
vagueness  of  them,  and  the  total  neglect  of  any  care  to  insure 
that  the  postulates  shall  be  sufficient  and  shall  be  indepen- 
dent of  one  another.  The  historian's  aim  is  at  bottom  quite 
different  from  that  of  the  student  of  Politics  or  sociology. 
They  are  concerned  with  the  "moral  "  of  the  fable;  the  true 
historian  only  cares  for  the  "  moral  "  in  a  wholly  secondary 
way.  He  knows  that  the  moralising  tendency  is  so  widely 
diffused  that  men  will  read  his  narrative,  as  too  many  of  them 
continue  to  read  Hamlet  or  Don  Quixote,  for  the  sake  of  the 
"  moral  "  to  be  got  out  of  it,  and  he  must  prefer  that  the 
"moral,"  since  moral  there  is  to  be,  should  be  one  in  con- 
formity with  the  actual  facts  and  not  otherwise.  But  his 
real  interest  is  with  the  story,  a  story  of  the  deeds  of  indi- 
vidual men  or  individual  societies  which  he  does  not  expect 
to  recur  and  does  not,  at  least  in  his  quality  of  historian, 


DIFFERENT  KINDS   OF   KNOWLEDGE?  455 

regard  as  /'  cases  "  or  ''instances"  of  a  law  of  tendency. 
They  may  very  well  be  that,  but  it  is  not  because  they  are 
that  that  he  takes  so  deep  an  interest  in  their  story.  One 
might,  for  example,  be  interested  in  the  History  of  the 
Roman  Empire  simply  as  a  striking  case  in  point  to  show 
how  what  is  at  bottom  a  military  usurpation,  under  a  con- 
stitutional mask,  comes  to  show  itself  in  its  true  character 
in  spite  of  the  ablest  attempts  of  the  most  intelligent  of  the 
wielders  of  the  usurped  power,  to  "  save  appearances  "  and 
to  hide  away  even  from  themselves  the  true  "secret  of  em- 
pire" ;  how  the  ultimate  break-down  of  this  attempt,  aided 
by  the  over-greatness  of  the  burden  to  be  borne  and  the 
tendency  of  new  social  strata  to  work  to  the  surface  and  of  new 
blood  to  find  its  way  into  the  boundaries  of  the  "civilised  " 
state,  leads  in  the  end  to  the  dissolution  of  the  institution 
itself.  But  it  is  plain  as  the  day  that  this  was  not  the  chief 
interest  which  the  tale  of  the  Decline  and  Fall  of  the  Eoman 
Empire  had  for  our  great  historian  of  it.  To  him  the  great 
interest  of  the  Empire  was  that  its  history  and  its  institutions 
were  the  source  of  so  much  in  the  life  and  institutions  of 
the  society  in  which  he  lived.  From  the  point  of  view  of  a 
pure  sociologist,  the  interest  of  the  Roman  Empire  and  its 
fortunes  should  be  quite  independent  of  the  "  empirical  "  fact 
that  its  historian  lived  in  the  Europe  of  the  eighteenth  cen- 
tury and  not  in  the  moon,  and  that  he  was  the  heir  of  the 
Graeco-Roman  tradition  of  life.  To  Gibbon  these  "tem- 
poral "  facts  made  nine-tenths  of  the  interest  of  his  subject. 
And  so  it  must  always  be  with  all  of  us.  Sub  specie  aeterni- 
tatis,  and  as  material  for  the  sociologist's  queries,  the  past 
of  China  or  Japan  may  be  as  important  as  that  of  France  or 
England  ;  for  us  who  are  Frenchmen  or  Englishmen  it  can- 
not possibly  be  so.  Just  so,  though  for  God  the  life  of  any 
man  may  have  as  much  interest  as  that  of  Dante  or  Chatham 
or  Knox,  it  cannot  be  and  ought  not  to  be  the  same  with  us 
who  are  the  heritors  of  what  they  did,  wisely  or  amiss.  It 
is  no  answer  to  repeat  the  old  story  that  whether  we  are 
contemplating  sub  specie  aeternitatis  or  sub  specie  temporis 
that  which  we  contemplate  is  in  either  case  the  same  thing, 
that  every  universal  is  also  particular  and  every  particular 
universal.  Even  if  this  were  true,  as  I,  for  my  part,  do  not 
believe  that  it  is,  the  observation  would  be  irrelevant.  It 
would  still  be  one  thing  to  study  the  particularity  of  the 
universal  and  another  to  study  the  universality  of  the  par- 
ticular. In  a  different  field  of  study,  it  may  be  true  that  our 
real  concern  with  a  great  philosopher  is  to  discover  what  he 
meant  to  say,  and  that  the  words  in  which  he  chose  to  say 


456          A.  E.  TAYLOR:  ARE  HISTORY  AND  SCIENCE 

it  are  a  secondary  matter,  but  every  scholar  would  subscribe 
to  the  statement  that  it  is  our  business  to  fix  the  text,  say  of 
Plato,  before  we  proceed  to  our  interpretation  and  that  in 
fixing  the  text  our  immediate  concern  is  not  with  what  we 
rightly  or  wrongly  suppose  to  be  the  "Platonic  philosophy," 
but  with  the  MSS.  and  the  ancient  testimonies.  In  history 
the  point  is  even  clearer  for  the  reason  I  have  just  given. 
Just  as  we  are  interested  in  our  own  relatives  and  friends 
and  enemies,  not  primarily  as  "  social  types  "  illustrative  of 
psychological  laws,  but  because  they  are  our  relatives  or 
friends  or  enemies,  we  are  legitimately  interested  in  the 
same  way  in  the  special  past  to  which  we  owe  our  own 
traditions,  and  in  a  lesser  degree  to  the  past  to  which  other 
races  of  men  owe  their  traditions,  because  it  is  the  past  of 
ourselves  or  of  our  fellow  human  sojourners  on  this  particular 
world  of  all  the  worlds  God  has  made.  The  past  of  a  race 
living  on  a  satellite  of  Sirius,  if  Sirius  has  satellites,  may 
reasonably  be  of  equal  value  as  illustrating  laws  of  tendency  : 
it  would  be  irrational  to  hold  that  it  can  have  the  same 
interest  for  us. 

I  have  dwelt  so  long  on  these  obvious  considerations  mainly 
because  they  ought  to  keep  us  from  introducing  false  methods 
of  study  into  history.  The  point  is  one  which  has  been 
made  admirably,  though  without  any  special  reference  to  the 
particular  problem  we  are  discussing,  in  Baron  von  Hiigel's 
wise  and  tender  essay,  Preliminaries  to  Eeligious  Belief 
(Essays  and  Addresses  on  the  Philosophy  of  Beligion,  pp.  98- 
118).  The  great  concern  in  science  is  that  the  postulates 
which  form  the  protases  of  our  statements  of  logical  implica- 
tion should  be  as  few  and  simple  as  the  case  permits  of.  (I 
should  say,  perhaps,  as  a  caution,  that  by  a  "  postulate  "  I 
mean  any  undemonstrated  proposition  used  as  an  ultimate 
premiss  in  science.  I  make  no  assumption  that  "  postulates  " 
may  properly  be  assumed  at  the  dictates  of  our  "  volitional 
nature,"  i.e.  because  we  should  like  to  assume  them,  still  less 
that  the  mere  making  of  the  "  postulate  "  in  any  way 
guarantees  its  truth.  I  am  using  the  word  in  the  mathema- 
tician's sense,  not  in  that  of  some  "philosophers  ".)  Hence 
strict  science  rightly  and  properly  follows  the  lead  of  Descartes 
in  insisting  that  its  postulates  shall  convey  "clear  and  dis- 
tinct "  ideas.  But  in  the  actual  growth  of  knowledge,  even 
about  our  fellow-men,  still  more  about  God,  as  von  Hugel 
rightly  insists,  we  never  begin  with  or  rest  our  knowledge  on 
"clear  and  distinct  ideas".  The  reality  with  which  we  are 
in  contact,  when  we  begin  as  infants  to  "  know  "  our  nurses 
and  parents,  wrhen  in  any  stage  of  life  we  have  the  religious 


DIFFEKENT  KINDS   OF   KNOWLEDGE?  457 

man's  direct  sense  of  touching  God,  is  in  its  nature  so  very 
rich  and  complex  that  our  "  knowledge  "of  it  is  bound  to  be 
inadequate  and  dim,  the  sort  of  "knowledge,"  as  the  same 
writer  says,  that  a  dog  has  of  its  master,  only  still  dimmer. 
Von  Hugel  is  specially  concerned  with  directing  this  argu- 
ment against  the  agnostic  in  theology  who  argues  that  be- 
cause our  supposed  knowledge  of  God  is  so  dim  and  confused, 
it  is  worth  nothing,  and  quite  probably  it  is  not  knowledge  of 
anything  at  all.  But  the  same  sort  of  considerations,  in  a 
lesser  degree,  are  applicable  to  the  study  of  human  history. 
Our  interest  in  the  men  and  the  ages  of  the  past  which  has 
shaped  the  traditions  under  which  we  live  is  of  the  same  kind, 
not  as  our  interest  in  the  observations  which  will  confirm  or 
refute  a  suspected  mathematical  law  or  a  formula  in  physics  or 
chemistry,  but  as  an  interest  in  our  personal  friends  and  foes. 

We  want,  quite  legitimately,  to  know  what  manner  of  men 
these  were ;  what  they  really  did ;  whether  the  benefit  or  the 
harm  accruing  to  us  from  their  deeds  was  foreseen  and  in- 
tended or  not,  and  if  not,  what  it  was  that  they  really  pur- 
posed. This  sort  of  interest  is  quite  unlike  that  of  the  strict 
follower  of  science ;  the  motive  at  the  bottom  of  it  is  quite 
different  from  his  passion  for  reducing  the  course  of  events 
to  law  and  formula.  A  statesman  may,  to  be  sure,  read  the 
history  of  the  past,  mainly  to  learn  from  it  how  to  shape  his 
own  path  among  the  uncertainties  of  life,  but  for  that  very 
reason,  his  interest  in  history  is  that  of  the  politician,  not 
that  of  the  historian.  At  bottom,  I  take  it,  we  all  want  to 
know  these  things  for  the  very  good  human  reason  that  we 
want  to  feel  gratitude  where  gratitude  is  deserved  and  not  to 
bestow  it  where  it-  would  be  wasted  on  the  undeserving. 
And  for  that  reason  we  properly  ask  of  a  great  historian 
something  we  should  never  demand  from  a  writer  on  science, 
just  as  we  ask  the  same  thing,  under  easier  conditions,  from 
a  great  novelist.  Of  the  man  of  science  we  ask  no  more  than 
that  he  should  "  explain"  the  course  of  things  to  us,  make  it 
smooth  and  easily  to  be  taken  in  as  a  whole,  by  showing  how 
it  all  follows  by  logical  deduction  from  a  few  simple  unproved 
principles  taken  in  conjunction  with  a  comparatively  few  close 
observations  of  actual  fact  as  a  " control".  If  history  were 
what  it  has  often  wrongly  been  taken  to  be,  disguised  political 
theory  or  even  disguised  "  sociology,"  we  ought  to  be  content 
to  ask  no  more  of  the  historian.  In  point  of  fact  we  do  ask 
something  more  and  very  different. 

We  expect  the  really  great  historian  not  merely  to  "  explain  " 
events  to  us  but  to  make  us  "  understand  "  the  doers  of  his- 
torical deeds.  He  must  bring  it  home  to  us  with  conviction 


458  A.   E.   TAYLOR  :    ARE   HISTORY  AND   SCIENCE 

what  manner  of  men  they  were,  who  were  doing,  and  what 
they  believed  themselves  to  be  doing.  Now  this  is  where 
"  science  "  inevitably  falls  short.  I  can  illustrate  my  point 
most  readily  by  an  obvious  example.  A  man  may  be  a 
thoroughly  "  scientific  "  psychologist  with  all  the  latest  theories 
and  laboratory  facts  at  his  fingers'  ends,  and  yet  he  might  be 
quite  incapable  of  telling  a  story  of  human  action,  even  one  in 
which  all  the  events  were  certified  "  facts,"  in  such  a  way  as 
to  make  us  accept  the  personages  of  the  story  as  "real"  ; 
they  might  impress  us  as  mere  products  of  the  laboratory 
with  labels  attached  to  them,  because,  as  we  should  probably 
say,  we  simply  cannot  "  understand  "  their  proceedings.  On 
the  other  hand,  men  who  have  probably  never  opened  a  book 
about  analytic  or  genetic  psychology  in  their  lives  can  tell  a 
tale  of  the  doings  and  feelings  of  quite  fictitious  characters  in 
a  way  which  makes  us  feel  that  we  "  understand  "  their  per- 
sonages all  through ;  we  can  enter  into,  or  as  Adam  Smith 
would  have  said,  "  go  along  with  "  all  they  say  or  do.  This 
is  why  we  call  the  fictitious  characters  in  such  men's  books 
"  real,"  and  often  speak,  with  some  ambiguity,  of  their  creators 
as  profound  "  psychologists  ".  So  they  are  in  a  sense,  but  it 
is  a  peculiar  sense ;  Henry  James  and  William  James  may 
both  be  called  "  psychologists,"  but  not  quite  in  the  same  sense 
of  the  word. 

Now  I  maintain  that  it  is  this  power  of  "  going  along  " 
with  the  actor  in  an  historical  scene  and  making  his  readers 
"go  along"  with  him,  which  may  be  wholly  wanting  in 
the  subtlest  analyst  of  situations  or  deviser  of  political 
theories,  that  is  the  supreme  gift  of  the  really  great  historian. 
And  it  is  not  a  gift  which  can  be  got  by  any  devotion  to 
"  scientific  method  ".  It  has  nothing  to  do  with  "  clear  and 
distinct  ideas  "  ;  which  of  us  has  what  the  logician  would 
pass  as  "  clear  and  distinct  ideas  "  of  his  most  intimate  friend  ? 
The  ordinary  good  Psychology  manual  will  give  you  much 
clearer  and  distincter  ideas  of  the  assumed  typical  man  whose 
mind  it  proposes  to  analyse  and  watch  as  it  grows.  But  you 
would  be  badly  at  sea  if  you  attempted  to  read  the  riddle  of 
a  real  man's  character  by  dependence  on  even  so  admirable  a 
textbook  as  the  Manual  of  my  colleague  Prof.  Stout,  as  I 
should  imagine  he  would  be  the  first  man  to  admit. 

I  do  not  mean,  of  course,  that  a  great  historian  is  a  brilliant 
novelist  under  another  name.  I  should  not  ask  anyone  to 
regard  the  very  brilliant  novel  called  "  Froude's  History  of 
England  "  or  the  hardly  less  brilliant  novel  of  Macaulay  as 
typical  historical  masterpieces.  The  historian  works  under  a 
control  from  which  the  novelist  is  free.  The  novelist  is  at 


DIFFEBENT  KINDS   OF   KNOWLEDGE?  459 

liberty  to  "  see"  his  characters  first  and  then  shape  the  course 
of  their  doings  to  correspond  to  his  vision.  The  historian  has 
to  start  by  "documenting"  himself  about  the  complicated 
web  of  events  and  then  to  divine  the  actors.  It  is  the  same 
process,  on  a  larger  scale  and  applied  to  the  past,  which  each 
of  us  performs  in  his  way,  when  he  judges  the  persons  among 
whom  his  life  is  cast  by  what  he  knows  of  their  words  and 
acts.  What  I  do  mean  is  that  the  performance  of  this  task 
is  incumbent  on  a  historian  and  that  it  is  success  in  it — 
success  in  making  us  "understand  " — which  stamps  the  really 
great  historian.  A  man  for  whom  the  acts  of  men  are  no 
more  than  events,  like  the  fall  of  a  cathedral  spire,  or  the 
occurrence  of  an  unexpected  storm  at  the  crisis  of  a  battle, 
might,  for  all  I  can  see,  quite  well  supply  the  student  of 
Political  Science  or  its  counterfeit  "  Sociology  "  with  materials 
for  constructing  more  or  less  sound  theories  about  "  social 
tendencies,"  but  no  man  will  be  an  historian  unless  he 
understands  that,  even  if  there  really  are  any  mere  "  events," 
the  acts  of  fully  awake  and  accountable  human  beings  are 
acts  and  not  mere  events  and  that  our  quite  unscientific  but 
quite  legitimate  interest  in  a  past  which  is  our  own  past  will 
not  be  satisfied  until  we  have  been  made  able  to  ''under- 
stand "  the  actor  behind  the  act.  For  this  reason,  though  I 
see  no  reason  why  the  historian  should  always  add  the  func- 
tion of  the  judge  to  his  own  and  insist  on  formally  pronounc- 
ing sentence  on  the  persons  with  whom  he  deals,  I  must 
confess  that  Lord  Acton  seems  to  me  to  have  understood  what 
is  properly  to  be  expected  of  an  historian  better  than  Seeley 
and  his  followers,  who  seem  to  think  that  when  the  work  of 
providing  Political  Science  with  materials  for  its  formulae  has 
once  been  done,  nothing  much  is  left  for  the  historian  but  to 
compose  "  Tales  of  a  Grandfather  ". 


III.  BY  F.  C.  S.  SCHILLEE. 

THE  theory  of  the  three-member  Symposium  is  supposed  to 
be  that  the  first  string  develops  his  Thesis,  the  second  harps 
upon  the  Antithesis,  while  upon  the  third  performer  devolves 
the  onerous  duty  of  finding  (if  he  can)  the  Higher  Synthesis 
which  resolves  their  discords.  In  practice,  however,  this 
is  so  arduous  an  undertaking  that  it  is  easier  to  make  a 
triangular  duel  of  it,  and  not  infrequently  it  happens  that 
the  aims  of  the  parties  are  so  little  co-ordinated  that  they 
attack,  not  one  problem,  but  three  or  more.  Usually  this 


460        F.    C.    S.    SCHILLEB :     AEE   HISTOEY  AND   SCIENCE 

comes  about  unintentionally,  owing  to  the  infirmity  of 
philosophic  purposes ;  but  on  this  occasion  I  understand 
that  Prof.  Taylor  wishes  us  to  legitimate  the  practice,  and 
consciously  to  aim  at  independent  treatment,  that  is,  to 
disregard  the  history  of  the  debate.  And  though  I  am  a 
little  apprehensive  that  this  procedure,  if  it  became  common, 
would  foster  in  '  symposiasts '  a  vice  to  which  philosophers 
are  all  too  prone,  that  of  solitary  drinking — I  mean,  of 
course,  thinking — in  the  present  case  I  have  no  difficulty  in 
complying  with  Prof.  Taylor's  request.  For,  sooth  to  say, 
I  find  that  my  predecessors  have  been  singularly  reasonable. 
They  have  abstained  from  firing  off  philosophic  paradoxes 
at  our  common  target,  and  from  bombarding  their  audience 
with  cryptic  conundrums.  Neither  of  them  has  asserted 
that  Science  alone  is  knowledge,  and  History  is  not,  or  that 
History  is  knowledge  and  Science  is  not.  Neither  has  as- 
serted that  Science  is  concerned  only  with  eternal  truth,  or 
that  History  has  no  relation  or  relevance  to  scientific  truth. 
Both  have  refrained  from  the  verbal  juggling  with  the  terms 
'  particular '  and  '  universal '  which  has  so  long  seemed  to 
be  the  sole  contribution  philosophy  could  make  to  any 
problem.1  Both  the  unity  of  knowledge  and  the  diversity 
of  its  kinds  have  been  upheld  in  quite  a  moderate  wTay. 

Consequently  it  would  not  have  been  easy  to  quarrel  with 
either  of  them,  though  incidentally  both  of  them  reveal 
that  they  do  not  quite  understand  pragmatism.  With  Mr. 
Collingwood's  attitude  indeed  I  find  myself  in  such  cordial 
agreement  that  I  can  accept  all  his  contentions,  though  I 
think  some  of  them  may  prove  misleading  unless  they  are 
safeguarded  and  supplemented  by  extensions  and  corollaries 
which  he  does  not  mention.  Prof.  Taylor's  interesting  paper 
I  could  not  swallow  so  whole-heartedly :  parts  of  it  should, 
I  think,  definitely  be  rejected.  But  my  reasons  for  so  doing 
are  so  very  simple  that  they  would  not  lend  themselves  to 
any  very  protracted  debate.  Accordingly  it  seems  quite 
possible  that  in  this  instance  dialectics  will  be  less  in- 
structive than  a  more  direct  approach  to  the  problem ; 

1 1  am  particularly  appreciative  of  their  abstention  from  this  practice, 
in  which  neither  term  was  ever  defined  or  distinguished  from  the  other. 
T3ut  if  we  cannot  say  wherein  either  particularity  or  universality  consists, 
what  is  the  use  of  predicating  either  of  anything?  And  further,  what 
meaning  can  it  have  to  say  that  everything  is  both  '  particular  '  and  *  uni- 
versal '  ?  If  that  is  so,  and  if  neither  '  particular '  nor  *  universal '  can  be, 
or  be  defined,  per  se,  the  distinction  between  them  becomes  an  arbitrary 
distinction  without  a  difference,  and  explanation  in  these  terms  is  mean- 
ingless. 


DIFFEEENT  KINDS   OF  KNOWLEDGE  ?  .  461 

at  any  rate  I  will  endeavour  to  develop  our  question  in- 
dependently and  shall  only  refer  incidentally  to  the  points 
where  my  predecessors'  treatment  seems  to  me  to  require 
comment. 

It  is  permissible  perhaps  to  begin  with  a  truism.  Our 
question  obviously  implies  that,  whether  or  not  Science  and 
History  are  identical,  they  are  not  wholly  different,  but 
relevant  to  each  other  and  to  the  nature  of  knowledge.  For 
if  they  were  not  different,  they  would  not  be  distinguished ; 
while  if  they  were  utterly  different,  they  could  not  be  com- 
pared, and  so  no  question  could  arise  as  to  the  precise  differ- 
ence between  our  cognitive  procedure  in  Science  and  in 
History.  It  is  also  antecedently  probable  that  such  differ- 
ences as  may  be  found  will  not  be  very  serious,  for  if  they 
were,  they  would  gravely  detract  from  the  unity  of  knowledge 
and  the  utility  of  recognising  it.  Further,  if  the  differences 
between  Science  and  History  are  not  serious,  it  will  be  a 
question  whether  they  are  to  be  dignified  with  the  title  of 
'  differences  in  kind  '. 

I  will  follow  up  my  first  truism  with  a  second,  which  ought 
to  be  deemed  its  equal.  Of  all  the  multitudinous  definitions 
an  object  of  inquiry  may  receive,  the  most  significant  is  one 
which  expresses  the  purpose  for  the  sake  of  which  it  has 
become  an  object  of  inquiry.  In  other  words,  in  order  really 
to  understand  the  nature  and  function  of  Science  and  of 
History,  we  must  discover  why  they  become  objects  of 
human  interest  and  to  what  ends  they  minister,  and  then 
define  them  accordingly.  If  they  serve  a  number  of  purposes 
and  have  several  ends,  it  will  be  necessary  to  evaluate  these 
ends,  and  to  decide  which  of  them  is  the  highest  and 
worthiest,  and  really  justifies  the  interest  taken  in  the  object. 
For  example,  food  is  probably  as  universal  an  object  of 
interest  as  can  be  found  among  men  ;  it  appeals  to  high  and 
low,  young  and  old,  savage  and  civilised,  and  much  is  said 
and  written  about  it.  It  has  interest  for  biology,  economics, 
ethics,  politics,  gastronomy,  physiology,  medicine  ;  nay  even 
for  theology,  seeing  that  the  earliest  religions  appear  to  have 
been  forms  of  food  magic.  It  is  evident,  however,  that  the 
ends  for  the  sake  of  which  men  are  interested  in  food  are  not 
all  of  equal  value. 

The  cases  of  Science  and  History  seem  similar.  Both  may 
be  pursued  for  various,  and  for  the  same,  ends.  Thus  some 
may  study  Science  and  some  History,  because  it  amuses 
them.  Others,  for  the  sake  of  a  livelihood.  The  former  end 
will  appeal  more  to  the  amateur,  the  latter  to  the  professional, 
Or  again,  both  Science  and  History  may  be  useful  to  the 


462      F.  c.  s.  SCHILLER:  ARE  HISTORY  AND  SCIENCE 

politician,  and  be  exploited  accordingly.  But  none  of  these 
ends  would  yield  a  very  adequate  definition  of  these  interests, 
and  they  would  certainly  not  enable  us  to  distinguish  between 
the  function  of  Science  and  of  History. 

We  must  therefore  try  again.  Perhaps  a  deeper  and  more 
specific  end  is  to  be  sought  in  the  functions  which  human 
life  is  enabled  to  fulfil  by  knowing  Science  and  History. 
What,  then,  is  the  vital  value  of  each?  Vital  value  both 
must  clearly  have,  in  some  way  or  other ;  otherwise  they 
could  not  maintain  themselves  as  spiritual  industries. 

Now  in  the  case  of  Science  the  answer  to  this  question 
has  become  pretty  obvious.  The  essential  characteristics  of 
scientific  knowledge,  which  distinguish  it  from  pseudo-science, 
divination,  guesswork,  metaphysics,  verbiage,  and  nonsense, 
are  prediction  and  control.  It  is  that  whereby  we  foresee 
the  future  and  calculate  the  distant,  and  guide  our  action 
accordingly.  It  is  the  knowledge  which  is  power,  and  which 
ministers  to  our  desire  for  power.  It  is  the  knowledge  which 
extends  our  power  beyond  the  present  into  the  future,  which 
forecasts  the  consequences  of  our  activities  and  enables  us 
to  foresee  what  will  happen  next.  It  liberates  us,  therefore, 
from  the  restriction  of  actual  experience  to  the  passing 
moment. 

This  achievement,  however,  is  not  enough.  It  is  not 
enough  to  know  the  real  as  it  is,  in  order  really  to  know  it, 
in  order  to  control  it.  We  must  know  also  what  it  will  be, 
and  what  it  has  been.  To  understand  the  actual  and  to 
treat  it  rightly,  we  must  extend  our  knowledge  backwards 
into  the  past,  and  regard  it  as  a  product  of  the  ages. 

We  ask,  therefore — how  has  the  actual  come  to  be  as  it 
is  ?  This  is  the  essential  question  which  History  tries  to 
answer.  Its  province  is  the  past ;  its  purpose  to  reveal  it, 
to  redeem  it  from  oblivion,  to  relate  it  to  the  present,  in 
order  that  we  may  have  the  power  over  things  that  comes 
from  knowledge  of  their  past.  It  follows  from  this  definition 
that  prophecy  is  not  the  primary  business  of  History ;  it 
leaves  this  to  Science,  which  is  not,  however,  restricted  to 
the  future ;  Science  can  calculate  the  past  as  well  as  the 
future,  though  only  with  the  aid  of  History.  The  ultimate 
aim  of  both,  however,  is  to  minister  to  our  need  of  controlling 
a  reality  that  kills  us  if  we  don't. 

If  these  definitions  be  accepted,  it  is  clear  what  the  differ- 
ence is  between  History  and  Science.  It  is  not,  however, 
inconsistent  with  its  recognition  to  add  a  warning  that  it 
does  not  imply  any  antagonism  between  Science  and  History, 
but  demands  their  close  co-operation.  Clearly  the  historian 


DIFFEEENT  KINDS   OF  KNOWLEDGE?  463 

may,  and  must,  use  all  the  technique  of  calculation  which 
Science  proffers,  to  reconstruct  the  past.  In  return,  the 
scientist  must  recognise  that,  in  all  that  concerns  the  past, 
he  needs  the  help  of  History. 

In  the  last  resort  this  means  that  he  needs  it  everywhere. 
A  birth-story  attaches  to  every  scientific  fact,  and  an  umbilical 
cord  once  connected  it  with  the  womb  of  time.  All  the 
data  out  of  which  scientific  '  facts  '  are  fabricated  are  primarily 
historical.  If  it  is  not  historically  true  that  a  certain  Mr. 
Dawson  once  found  certain  bones  at  a  certain  distance  from 
each  other  in  a  certain  deposit,  the  Piltdown  skull  was  that  of 
a  man  and  the  teeth  were  those  of  an  ape,  and  Eoanthropus 
Dawsoni  cannot  be  put  together,  and  becomes  a  myth.  If  it 
is  not  true  that  trustworthy  observers  have  seen  the  fall  of 
meteorites,  Laplace  was  right  to  argue  that  '  there  are  no 
stones  in  heaven,  ergo  none  can  fall  from  heaven  '.  If  seers 
of  ghosts  and  witnesses  of  miracles  are  always  liars,  the  beliefs 
based  on  ghosts  and  miracles  fall  to  the  ground.  In  short, 
the  truth  is  that  all  scientific  laws  presuppose  scientific  facts, 
and  all  scientific  facts  presuppose  historical  facts ;  thus  every 
known  '  law  of  nature  '  would  crumble  or  evaporate  if  a 
limited  (and  usually  quite  a  small)  number  of  historical 
observations  should  be  rejected  as  untrustworthy.  Every 
scientific  truth,  therefore,  has  a  past  and  a  history,  on  which 
it  remains  dependent. 

But  every  scientific  truth  also  hopes  to  have  a  future.  It 
means  to  remain  true.  It  has  the  ambition  and  the  duty  to 
predict :  it  claims  to  regulate  a  course  of  events  which  it 
admits  to  be  unique.  The  idea  that  a  scientific  law  is  a 
timeless  formula,  having  eternal  truth  or  validity  and  exempt 
from  all  obligation  to  embody  or  exemplify  itself  in  the  flux 
of  events  is  a  philosophic  blunder,  a  blunder  which  scientists 
repudiate,  because  they  know  that  the  time-relation  is  left  a 
blank  only  in  order  that  their  *  law  '  may  be  applied  to  and  at 
any  time.  It  retains  a  certain  popularity  among  philosophers 
who  have  learnt  nothing  since  the  days  of  Plato ;  but  I  am 
glad  to  see  that  my  colleagues  are  not  of  this  kind.  Mr. 
Collingwood  is  quite  explicit  in  repudiating  the  notion  that 
the  whole  business  of  Science  is  to  generalise  and  that  it  has 
no  concern  with  the  particular :  its  function  is  to  interpret 
particulars  by  means  of  generalisations.  And  he  makes  this 
his  chief  ground  for  denying  any  essential  difference  between 
Science  and  History.  Prof.  Taylor,  too,  admits  that  it  can 
be  argued  that  "the  universal  truths  of  science  hold  true  of 
individual  cases,"  though  he  would  not,  perhaps,  admit  that 
they  are  meaningless  unless  they  do.  As,  however,  unlike 


464      F.  c.  s.  SCHILLER:  ABE  HISTORY  AND  SCIENCE 

Mr.  Collingwood,  he  wishes  to  stress  the  difference  between 
Science  and  History,  he  adopts  an  ideal  of  '  pure  '  science, 
of  which  that  can  be  alleged  which  is  manifestly  false  of 
actual  science.  '  Pure  '  science  has  no  truck  with  '  fact,'  and 
no  connexion  with  '  applied'.  It  takes  no  dip  in  the  great 
stream  of  events.  Being  purely  '  hypothetical/  it  has  no 
relation  with  '  pure  '  history,  which  tries  to  be  '  categorical '. 
But  it  has  not  occurred  to  him  that  if  so,  '  pure '  science 
will  neither  work  nor  wash ;  it  is  pure  fiction  and  a  creature 
of  abstraction.  It  is  futile  fiction  and  false  abstraction.  For 
the  '  pure  '  principles  must  be  used,  and  the  pure  science 
be  applied.  Moreover,  Prof.  Taylor's  point  can  not  be  proved 
thus ;  for  to  show  that '  pure '  science  and  '  pure  '  history  have 
no  relation,  either  with  each  other  or  with  our  purposes,  is  no 
proof  that  actual  Science  and  History  are  not  interdependent 
and  intended  to  co-operate  with  each  other  and  with  us. 
The  actual  collaboration  of  actual  science  and  actual  history 
Prof.  Taylor  does  not  appear  to  deny :  it  is  only  as  *  pure ' 
abstractions  that  they  are  irreconcilable.  And  this  is  merely 
a  way  of  saying  that  these  abstractions  are  unreal  and  use- 
less ;  they  do  not  serve  to  elucidate  the  actual  functioning  of 
knowledge,  in  which  all  our  activities  play  into  each  other's 
hands. 

Nevertheless  there  are  differences  between  Science  and 
History,  and  they  should  not  be  overlooked.  We  should 
note  in  the  first  place  that,  though  both  aim  at  an  unambigu- 
ous account  of  their  subject-matter,  neither  of  them  quits' 
succeeds.  Science,  though  it  assumes,  as  a  postulate  of 
method,  that  the  future  is  fixed  and  unambiguously  calcul- 
able, does  not  succeed  in  predicting  it  completely.  It  ascribes 
this  failure,  quite  consistently,  to  the  infirmity  of  human 
knowledge,  and  not  to  any  inherent  recalcitrance  of  the  real, 
or  any  impossibility  of  predicting  the  course  of  an  indeter- 
minate agent.  But  despite  this  explanation,  the  fact  remains 
that  our  science  cannot  fully  determine  the  future. 

At  first  sight  we  are  better  off  in  regard  to  the  past.  We 
are  accustomed  to  say  that  though  the  future  may  be,  or 
seem,  contingent,  at  any  rate  the  past  is  fixed  unalterably. 
It  is  dead  and  done  with,  and  what  is  done  cannot  be  un- 
done, even  by  the  gods.  History  is  a  record  that  stands,  and 
cannot  be  shaken.  All  these  beliefs  are  dangerous  delusions. 
They  spring  from  illusions  that  rest  upon  a  false  abstraction. 
We  can  abstractly  conceive  the  past  as  existing  per  se  and 
apart  from  our  means  of  knowing  it ;  if  we  do  this,  we  can 
represent  it  as  determinate  and  unalterable. 

But  such  is  not  the  character  of  the  past  as  known. 


DIFFEBENT  KINDS   OF   KNOWLEDGE?  465 

The  past  in  which  we  believe,  and  which  we  believe  our 
histories  to  record,  is  not  the  object  of  an  assured,  deter- 
minate and  definitive  knowledge.  It  is  always  incomplete, 
dubious,  undetermined.  Its  history  is  only  a  hypothetical 
reconstruction,  often  highly  imaginative,  out  of  utterly  in- 
adequate material.  The  more  the  logical  character  of  his- 
torical evidence  is  examined,  the  more  unsatisfactory  it 
seems.  It  is  full  of  bias,  folly,  error,  discrepancy  and  contra- 
diction. There  is  always  too  little  evidence  for  it,  and  usually 
too  much.  For  so  much  of  the  evidence  is  so  bad  and  un- 
enlightening.  The  historian  therefore  has  to  appraise  and 
select  at  every  step,  and  if  he  compiles  a  plausible  tale — 
perhaps  only  a  fable  convenue  or  a  masterpiece  of  propaganda 
—he  is  acclaimed  as  great.  Another  may  achieve  as  much, 
and  then  we  can  accept  whichever  tale  we  please.  For  there 
is  no  verification  of  either,  as  in  Science,  and  no  crucial  test. 
The  only  verification  History  can  claim  lies  in  alleging 
nothing  grossly  improbable,  and  nothing  from  which  our 
actual  present  could  not  have  followed.  It  must  not  be  said 
that  Hannibal,  not  Brennus,  captured  Rome  and  burnt  it. 
For  if  he  had,  Mediterranean  man  would  presumably  now 
be  speaking  a  Semitic,  not  a  Latin,  tongue. 

But  this  verification  by  consonance  with  the  actual  is 
wholly  insufficient.  A  thousand  histories,  all  different, 
might  equally  conduct  to  the  actual  facts.  When  therefore 
we  look  back  upon  the  past,  a  thousand  threads  of  historical 
sequence  radiate  from  the  present  into  the  past.  There  are 
a  thousand  roads  which  we  might  follow.  Which  of  them 
shall  we  choose  as  the  '  true  '  history,  to  lead  us  to  the  past  as 
it  '  really  was '  and  changes  not  ?  We  do  not  know.  We 
cannot  know.  Actually,  we  choose  the  history  which  seems 
to  us  most  promising  and  congenial;  we  choose  with  the 
character,  the  intelligence,  the  knowledge,  the  prejudices, 
the  history,  we  have.  Is  it  astonishing  that  we  choose  differ- 
ently, that  the  fashions  change  in  history  as  in  medicine, 
and  that  all  the  really  important  questions,  i.e.,  those  which 
are  felt  vitally  to  affect  the  present,  remain  matters  of  partisan 
debate?  Actually,  therefore,  the  past  is  for  us  as  indeter- 
minate as  the  future  :  the  determination  of  both  remains  an 
overbelief  which  does  not  debar  us,  in  either  case,  from 
reckoning  with  alternatives. 

So  far  the  scientist  and  the  historian  appear  to  be,  very 
definitely,  in  the  same  boat,  even  though  they  do  not  row  on 
the  same  side  of  it.  The  scientist,  however,  has  one  definite 
advantage.  The  verification  of  a  historical  hypothesis, 
which  deduces  the  actual  from  what  is  judged  to  be  the  best 

30 


466  F.   C.    S.    SCHILLEE  I    HISTORY  AND   SCIENCE. 

interpretation  of  the  evidence,  was,  we  saw,  very  imperfect, 
and  if  any  portion  of  the  structure  is  insecure,  there  is  no  help 
for  it.  Nothing  can  be  done,  because  History  cannot  be  re- 
enacted,  and  observed  afresh.  It  never  quite  repeats  itself, 
because  if  it  tried  to,  the  very  fact  that  it  had  occurred  before 
would,  if  it  were  remembered,  alter  the  result.  Hence  the 
historian  cannot  experiment.  The  scientist  can.  If  he  is  not 
satisfied  with  the  evidence  for  his  hypothesis,  he  can  devise 
fresh  tests,  or  repeat  the  old  ones.  True,  such  repetition  is 
never  absolute,  and  a  theoretic  quibbler  may  always  object 
that  therefore  the  case  may  not  turn  out  to  be  the  '  same,'  nor 
indeed  a  case  at  all,  of  the  theory  under  examination.  But 
experience  shows  that  over  extensive  fields  of  scientific  re- 
search the  conditions  practically  can  be  repeated  and  the 
differences  between  the  various  experiments  rendered  minimal 
and  irrelevant.  Hence  verification  is  a  much  more  potent 
weapon  in  Science  than  in  History,  though  even  in  Science 
no  amount  of  verification  of  a  '  law  of  nature '  by  subsequent 
fact  suffices  to  prove  it  absolutely  true.1 

The  truth,  therefore,  both  of  Science  and  of  History  is 
pragmatic ;  it  is  established  in  the  same  way  as  the  rest  of 
our  knowledge.  In  ultimate  analysis  there  is  but  one  truth, 
and  one  way  of  ascertaining  it.  There  are  differences  in  the 
working  of  our  method  in  Science  and  in  History  ;  but  these 
are  due  to  the  different  recalcitrance  of  the  material  to  our 
various  purposes.  In  the  end,  however,  Science  and  History 
stand  and  fall  together ;  and  I  at  least  can  conceive  no 
worthier  aim  for  a  philosopher  than  to  stand  by  both. 

1  In  regard  to  mathematical  l  truth '  it  may  be  observed,  (1)  that  to 
admit  that  it  is  deducible  from  postulates  which  are  *  arbitrary '  (in  the 
sense  of  admitting  alternatives)  is  an  admission  that  it  is  not  absolute, 
while  (2)  the  necessity  of  accounting  for  the  actual  choice,  of  postulates 
imposes  empirical  conditions  on  its  truth.  For  the  postulate-systems 
preferred  are  either  chosen  on  subjective  grounds,  or  are  those  which 
have  shown  themselves  convenient  and  useful  in  the  interpretation  of  our 
experience.  Their  empirical  validation,  however,  disposes  of  the  Platonic 
charge  that  the  principles  of  the  sciences  are  arbitrary  and  insecure. 
They  would  be  arbitrary  only  if  they  were  chosen  without  rhyme  or 
reason,  they  would  be  insecure,  only  if  they  had  not  received  overwhelm- 
ing confirmation  from  the  working  of  the  sciences. 


IV.— SYMBOLISM  AS  A  METAPHYSICAL 
PRINCIPLE.1 

BY  WILLIAM  TEMPLE,  BISHOP  OF  MANCHESTEE. 

IT  is  abundantly  clear  that  one  of  the  chief  characteristics  of 
contemporary  philosophy  is  the  place  which  it  gives  to  the 
concept  of  Value.  There  is  nothing  unprecedented  in  this. 
Indeed  it  is  not  possible  to  give  a  higher  place  to  Value  than 
Plato  did  when  he  made  the  Good  the  supreme  principle  in 
reality  or  required  of  Anaxagoras  that,  in  order  to  illustrate  the 
supremacy  of  Keason,  he  should  prove  the  earth  to  be  either 
round  or  fiat  by  showing  which  it  is  better  that  it  should  be. 
Aristotle,  whom  no  one  has  yet  censured  for  sentimentalism, 
similarly  clinches  his  argument  for  the  Unity  of  God  or  the 
governing  principle  with  the  maxim  and  the  quotation :  ra 
&e  ovra  ov  ffovXerai,  Tro^neveaOai  /ea^rco?.  "  ov/c  ayaObv 
7ro\vKO{,pavirj  •  el?  /coupavos  eVra)."  But  though  not  un- 
precedented, the  prominence  of  Value  in  the  thought  of  our 
time  is  characteristic.  To  the  religious  thinker,  it  is  welcome. 
And  yet  there  is  a  remarkable  indefiniteness  in  the  current 
use  of  the  term,  and  the  relation  of  Value  to  Eeality  or 
Substance  is  by  most  writers  either  not  discussed  or  is  very 
sketchily  outlined.  The  aim  of  this  paper  is  to  offer  a  very 
small  contribution  to  the  discussion  of  these  questions. 


I. 

The  structure  of  Eeality,  as  it  presents  itself  to  us,  seems 
to  be  as  follows :  It  consists  of  many  grades,  of  which  each 
presupposes  those  lower  than  itself,  and  of  which  each  finds 
its  own  completion  or  perfect  development  only  in  so  far  as 
it  is  possessed  or  indwelt  by  that  which  is  above  it.  This 
seems  to  involve  an  infinite  regress,  and  suggests  an  infinite 
progress.  Whether  there  is  in  fact  a  lowest  and  a  highest 
term  in  this  scale  of  finite  existences  I  do  not  know,  and  I 
do  not  greatly  care.  In  a  book  of  mine  called  Mens  Creatrix 
I  have  tried  to  show  that  the  infinite  series  is  not  necessarily 
meaningless  in  logic  or  futile  in  ethics.  At  present  I  am  not 

1  Contributed  to  the  Joint  Session  of  the  Mind  Association  and  the 
Aristotelian  Society  at  Manchester,  July  14th- 16th,  1922. 


468  WILLIAM  TEMPLE  : 

concerned  with  the  problem  of  lowest  and  highest  terms,  but 
with  the  facts  before  us,  which  may  fall  midway  between 
such  terms.  I  am  rather  tabulating  impressions  than  con- 
structing a  system,  though  the  tabulation  is  of  interest 
because  it  suggests  the  principle  of  a  system.  To  make 
my  present  meaning  clear  it  will  be  enough  to  take  the  broad 
divisions :  Matter,  Life,  Mind,  Spirit.  These  grades  may 
be  for  our  present  purpose  indifferently  regarded  as  various 
entities  or  as  different  modes  of  action  and  re-action.  Matter 
is  itself  a  term  covering  many  grades ;  so  is  Life.  But  each 
has  sufficient  identity  in  itself  and  sufficient  distinctness  from 
the  others  for  the  requirements  of  the  argument. 

The  term  Matter  is  here  taken  to  cover  the  substances  or 
the  modes  of  action  and  re-action  which  are  studied  in  the 
sciences  of  Physics  and  Chemistry.  It  is  at  once  quite  clear 
that  those  sciences  give  no  account  of  the  self-movement 
which  is  one  characteristic  of  Life,  or  of  the  comprehension 
of  spaces  and  times  which  is  one  characteristic  of  Mind* 
The  lower  cannot  explain  the  higher.  But  that  is  not  all. 
The  living  organism  has  in  its  material  constitution  a  unity 
of  differences,  a  subtlety  of  co-ordination,  a  spontaneity  of 
adaptation,  that  no  knowledge  of  Physics  and  Chemistry 
would  enable  the  observer  to  anticipate.  The  material  only 
reveals  its  full  potentialities  when  Life  possesses  and  indwells 
it.  The  later  development  reveals  what  had  all  along  been 
potential  in  the  earlier ;  but  no  knowledge  of  the  earlier  apart 
from  that  development  would  have  made  possible  a  prediction 
of  the  development.  Matter  only  reveals  what  it  really  is 
when  Life  supervenes  upon  it. 

Similarly  Life  only  reveals  what  it  really  is  when  Mind 
supervenes  upon  it.  No  study  of  zoology  and  biology  will 
enable  the  student  to  predict  the  occurrence  among  living 
things  of  Shakespeare  or  Bach  or  Leonardo  or  Newton.  The 
use  of  faculties,  which  at  first  are  used  for  mere  survival,  in 
the  interest  of  ends  that  have  nothing  at.  all  to  do  with 
survival,  must  occur  in  fact  before  it  can  be  anticipated  in 
theory.  So  too  Mind  as  intellect  only  shows  what  it  can  be 
and  do  when  it  is  guided  by  Mind  as  Spirit.  The  existence  of 
Art  and  Science,  though  they  make  upon  Life  an  absolute 
claim,  will  not  account  for  the  self-sacrifice  of  the  hero  or  the 
martyr.  And,  if  Religion  is  to  be  trusted,  even  Spirit  (as 
known  in  our  experience)  only  reveals  what  it  can  be  and  do 
when  it  is  possessed  by  that  Highest  Being,  whom  we  call 
Spirit  because  Spirit  is  the  highest  grade  of  Reality  known 
to  us. 

We  begin  then  with  the  conception  of  Eeality  as  existing 


SYMBOLISM  AS  A  METAPHYSICAL   PRINCIPLE.  469 

in  many  grades,  each  of  which  finds  its  own  completion  or 
perfect  development  only  in  so  far  as  it  is  possessed  or 
indwelt  by  that  which  is  above  it.  But  we  then  notice 
that  each  depends  for  its  actuality  upon  those  which  are 
below  it.  Matter  itself  as  experienced  by  us  can  be  reduced 
to  what  is  simpler  than  itself,  whether  to  a,  /3  and  7 
particles  or  still  more  ultimately  to  Space-Time.  Life  is 
unknown  apart  from  living  organisms,  which  are  Matter 
informed  by  Life.  Mind  is  unknown  except  in  reasoning 
living  organisms.  Spirit  is  unknown  except  in  conscientious, 
reasoning,  living  organisms.  Whether  the  higher  grades 
can  exist  apart,  there  seems  to  be  no  means  of  deciding;  in 
our  experience  they  never  do. 

Thus  we  see  each  grade  dependent  for  its  existence  on  the 
grades  below,  and  dependent  for  its  own  full  actualisation  on 
the  grade  or  grades  above.  Such  seems,  apart  from  any 
theory  of  its  origin  or  raison  d'etre,  to  be  in  fact  the  structure 
of  Eeality. 

II. 

At  this  point  I  must  ask  leave  to  assume  that  when  we  ask 
for  an  explanation  of  the  Universe  as  a  whole  we  are  bound 
to  formulate  the  answer  in  terms  of  Will.  To  summarise 
very  briefly  the  argument  by  which  I  should  seek  to  justify 
this  assumption,  I  would  submit  that  there  is  in  our  ex- 
perience one,  and  only  one,  self-explanatory  principle — 
namely  Purpose  or  Will :  no  doubt,  if  anyone  can  believe 
in  a  purpose  with  no  will  behind  it,  we  should  have  to  say 
"  Purpose  "  only,  leaving  "  Will  "  as  a  precarious  inference ; 
but  as  it  appears  that  Purpose  and  Will  are  terms  that 
mutually  imply  each  other,  we  may  speak  of  either  in- 
differently. There  is  a  "problem  of  evil,"  but  there  is  not 
in  the  same  sense  any  problem  of  good.  When  we  find  as 
the  cause  of  any  phenomenon  an  intelligent  will  which  chose 
to  cause  that  phenomenon  to  occur,  we  raise  no  further  ques- 
tions, unless  we  fail  to  see  how  that  will  came  to  seek  this 
occurrence  as  good.  We  may  be  puzzled  by  the  way  a  man 
exercises  choice ;  but  our  problem  here  is  not  as  a  rule  a 
problem  of  efficient  causation.  When  we  sympathise,  we  are 
not  puzzled.  If  I  say  of  anyone  "  I  cannot  understand  acting 
like  that,"  I  do  not  mean  that  I  cannot  give  a  psychological 
analysis  of  the  motives  of  the  action  ;  I  mean  that  I  cannot 
imagine  myself  doing  it.  When  in  the  causal  regress  we 
arrive  at  a  will,  the  regress  is  at  an  end,  and  to  understand 
means,not  to  give  a  causal  explanation,  but  to  sympathise. 


470  WILLIAM  TEMPLE: 

We  have  reached  an  ultimate  term.  And  when  we  do 
sympathise,  our  mind  raises  no  more  questions.  The  only 
explanation  of  the  Universe  that  would  really  explain  it,  in 
the  sense  of  providing  to  the  question  why  it  exists  an  answer 
that  raises  no  further  question,  would  be  the  demonstration 
that  it  is  the  creation  of  a  Will  which  in  the  creative  act 
seeks  an  intelligible  good.  But  that  is  Theism.  Theism  of 
some  kind  is  the  only  theory  of  the  universe  which  could 
really  explain  it.  Theism  may  be  untenable ;  if  it  is,  the 
universe  is  inexplicable.  Merely  to  show  how  it  fits  together 
as  a  rational  system  does  not  explain  it,  for  we  are  left  still 
asking — why  does  it  exist  at  all  ?  When  once  that  question 
is  asked  the  answer  must  be  found  in  Theism  or  nowhere. 

I  need  hardly  say  that  I  do  not  advance  this  outline  argu- 
ment either  as  the  only  defence  of  Theism  or  as  a  sufficient 
intellectual  basis  for  it.  The  whole  body  of  argument  that 
is  articulated  by  Prof.  Pringle-Pattison  and  Prof.  Sorley  in 
their  Gifford  Lectures,  or  by  Mr.  Matthews  in  his  recently 
published  Boyle  Lectures,  is  here  presupposed.  But  the 
point  which  I  have  just  mentioned,  and  which  deserves  more 
attention  in  my  judgment  than  it  generally  receives,  is  the 
one  most  germane  to  the  group  of  considerations  with  which 
we  are  now  specially  concerned.  Other  arguments  seem  to 
establish  the  principle  that  the  universe  must  be  interpreted 
by  spiritual  rather  than  by  mechanical  or  other  materialistic 
categories.  Other  arguments  tend  to  establish  the  ethical 
character  of  the  spiritual  power  or  powers  that  govern  the 
world.  Philosophically  everything  is  ready  for  Theism.  But 
actual  belief  in  a  living  God  rests  primarily,  as  I  think,  on 
religious  experience,  and  finds  its  intellectual  support  in  the 
reflexion  that  this  belief  is  capable  in  principle  of  supplying 
an  explanation  of  the  very  existence  of  the  Universe,  which  no 
other  hypothesis  available  to  us  affords  any  hope  of  doing. 
That  is  no  proof.  It  cannot  be  laid  down  as  an  axiom  that 
there  must  be  some  explanation  of  the  existence  of  the 
Universe.  If  the  existing  scheme  of  things  be  internally 
coherent,  it  cannot  be  said  that  the  mind  imperiously 
demands  more  than  this  for  its  satisfaction.  It  is  true 
that  we  have  to  choose  between  postulating  a  rational  uni- 
verse and  accepting  complete  scepticism.  It  is  not  true  that 
we  have  to  choose  between  theism  and  scepticism.  I  should 
be  very  sorry  to  have  to  believe  that  Reality  is  what  Mr. 
Bradley  describes  or  even  what  Prof.  Pringle-Pattison 
describes.  But  I  could  not  reject  their  accounts  of  it  only 
on  the  ground  that  they  do  not  explain  its  existence  as  a 
whole.  For  while  it  is  an  additional  advantage  in  any  theory 


SYMBOLISM  AS  A  METAPHYSICAL   PEINCIPLE.  471 

if  it  can  do  this,  it  is  not  fatal  to  any  theory  that  it  should 
fail  to  do  this,  or  even  refuse  to  attempt  it.  It  may  be  that 
there  is  no  explanation  of  Eeality  itself,  and  that  it  is  "not 
self-explanatory  except  in  the  sense  that  all  its  parts  support 
each  other  in  constituting  the  whole.  Or,  again,  it  may  be 
that  there  is  an  explanation  of  Reality,  but  that  it  is  some- 
thing wholly  inaccessible  to  the  mind  of  man.  There  seems 
no  reason  to  suppose  that  mind,  in  its  human  manifestation, 
either  includes,  or  itself  is,  the  last  term  in  cosmic  evolution, 
and  if  there  is  more  to  follow,  then  though  human  mind  would 
comprehend  the  lower  forms  it  would  not  know  at  all  what 
constituted  the  higher  forms,  and  it  would  be  in  these,  not  in 
human  mind,  that  the  explanation  of  Reality  might  be  found. 
None  the  less,  if  there  is  an  available  hypothesis  which  is 
capable  in  its  own  nature  of  supplying  the  explanation  of 
Reality,  it  is  thoroughly  scientific  to  experiment  with  it  and 
see  if  it  can  make  good  its  claim.  Now  Purpose,  as  the 
expression  of  a  Will,  is  such  a  principle.  But  to  seek  the 
explanation  of  the  Universe  in  a  Purpose  grounded  in  a  Will 
is  Theism  ;  it  is  the  acceptance,  provisionally  at  least,  of  the 
doctrine  of  God  as  Creator.  From  religion  there  comes 
abundant  support  for  this  doctrine.  To  some  religions,  and 
notably  to  the  Jewish  and  Christian  religions,  it  is  essential 
and  fundamental. 

III. 

Now  if  we  assume  the  structure  of  Reality  to  be  such  as 
I  have  outlined,  and  if  we  accept  (at  least  for  purposes  of 
enquiry)  the  explanation  of  it  which  Theism  offers,  certain 
consequences  follow,  which  it  is  the  main  purpose  of  this 
paper  to  trace  out. 

Will  acts  always  for  the  sake  of  value,  or  good,  to  be  created 
or  enjoyed  as  a  result  of  the  action.  It  is  precisely  as  so  acting 
that  it  is  self-explanatory  and  intrinsically  intelligible.  This 
would  lead  us  to  expect  that  whatever  Will  creates  is  either 
itself  good  or  is  a  means  to  good.  Moreover  if  what  is 
created  is  good  not  (or  not  only)  as  a  means  but  in  itself,  this 
means  that  its  very  being  or  substance  is  good.  I  do  not,  at 
present,  go  so  far  as  to  say  that  good  is  the  being  or  substance 
of  all  that  exists,  but  we  are  entitled  and  even  bound  by  the 
hypothesis  adopted  to  say  that  whatever  exists  must  either 
be  a  means  to  something  which  is  substantially  good  or  else 
be  itself  substantially  good.  We  seem  therefore  to  be  led  up 
to  a  new  enquiry  into  the  relations  of  value  and  reality. 

Now  if  I  may  take  Prof.  Pringle-Pattison  as  an  illustrious 
example  of  contemporary  philosophy,  and  discuss,  not  the 


472  WILLIAM   TEMPLE  : 

details  of  his  argument,  nor  its  claims  taken  as  a  whole,  but 
the  general  impression  created  by  it  on  my  own  mind,  and 
also  (as  I  find)  on  many  other  minds,  I  would  venture  to 
suggest  that  many  of  the  anxieties  with  regard  to  it  which 
that  general  impression  arouses  would  vanish  if  he  saw  his 
way  to  a  more  thorough-going  conception  of  God  in  terms  of 
Will.  For  the  general  impression  left  on  my  mind  by  his 
great  book  on  the  Idea  of  God,  and  greatly  strengthened  by 
his  essay  in  the  volume  entitled  The  Spirit,  is  that  he  accepts 
the  Universe  as  somehow  existing,  and  then  finds  that  it 
reveals  values,  which  are  regarded  all  the  while  as  being 
adjectival  to  it.  That  they  appear  at  all  is  a  determinant 
consideration  for  the  philosopher,  and  yet  they  appear  rather 
as  appendices  of  an  otherwise  existing  universe  than  as  them- 
selves its  constitutive  elements ;  and  when  we  reach  the 
Being  in  whom  all  values  are  realised,  He  hovers  uncertainly 
between  two  positions,  being  at  one  time  the  Ground  of  all 
existence  and  at  another  a  characteristic  of  a  universe  which 
would  apparently  continue  to  exist  (though  shorn  of  its 
values)  if  He  were  to  cease.  And  it  is  the  latter  position 
to  which  He  seems  to  be  ultimately  relegated.  I  have  no 
doubt  that  this  summary  is  unjust  to  Prof.  Pringle-Pattison. 
Almost  any  summary  of  a  theory  elaborated  with  so  delicate 
a  balance  and  an  argument  so  closely  knit  would  be  unjust. 
But  at  the  end  of  The  Idea  of  God  I  was  left  with  a  sense 
that  this  book  makes  God  adjectival  to  the  Universe,  and  the 
essay  in  The  Spirit  removed  all  doubt  on  the  question.  And 
yet  I  was  sure  that  in  the  main  the  Professor  was  dealing 
with  the  matter  on  right  lines  and  had  rendered  a  great 
service  to  philosophy,  and  especially  the  philosophy  of  re- 
ligion, by  following  the  method  which  he  had  chosen. 

The  question  with  which  I  am  now  concerned  is  this : 
should  we  conceive  of  things  as  existing  independently  and 
possessing  value  as  an  attribute,  or  should  we  think  of  value 
as  itself  the  true  reality  which  realises  its  various  forms 
through  embodying  itself  in  things — or  through  the  creation 
of  things  for  this  purpose  by  the  Divine  Will  ? 

Now  I  believe  that  our  difficulty  arises  from  the  fact  that 
Philosophy  being  an  intellectual  activity,  always  tends  to 
depend  more  upon  that  search  for  an  ultimate  value  which  is 
conducted  in  science  than  upon  the  two  kindred  efforts  of 
ethics  and  of  art.  In  science  the  intellect  is  not  only  supreme 
but  sole ;  it  is  natural  for  the  intellect  to  take  the  methods 
and  operations  of  science  not  only  as  its  method  but  also  as 
determining  the  subject-matter  of  its  enquiry.  That  I  take 
to  be  the  essential  feature  of  the  heresy  of  intellectualism. 


SYMBOLISM  AS  A  METAPHYSICAL   PEINCIPLE.  473 

Philosophy  must  be  intellectual  or  it  ceases  to  be  itself.  But 
the  intellect  always  gets  its  subject-matter  from  outside 
itself ;  it  is  ready  enough  to  accept  it  from  the  physical 
world,  and  from  its  own  procedure  and  results  in  dealing 
with  the  physical  world.  It  is  less  ready  to  accept  as  the 
material  of  its  operations  the  procedure  and  results  of  human 
activities  which  are  either  not  purely  or  not  at  all  intellectual. 
Yet  for  a  satisfactory  metaphysic  it  must  include  these,  and 
indeed  (as  I  think)  must  give  them  a  determining  influence. 
The  goal  of  Science  is  on  the  objective  side  Keality,  on  the 
subjective  side  Knowledge ;  the  goal  of  Art  is  on  the  objective 
side  Beauty,  on  the  subjective  side  Creation  and  Appreciation ; 
the  goal  of  Ethics  is  on  the  objective  side  Society,  on  the 
subjective  side  enlightened  Conscience  and  dutiful  Action. 
It  is  apparent  that  whereas  Science  ends  in  Knowledge, 
which  leaves  the  objective  world  as  it  finds  it,  Art  and  Ethics 
— and  Eeligion — aim  both  at  a  comprehension  of  the  object 
and  at  action  which  modifies  the  object.  Now  if  the  intellect 
is  led  by  its  own  process  to  the  affirmation,  or  at  least  to  the 
supposition,  that  the  explanation  of  the  Universe  is  to  be 
found  in  the  activity  of  a  Creative  Will,  it  must  go  on  to 
accept  those  human  activities  which  include  some  creative 
energy  as  surer  guides  to  the  constitution  of  Reality  than  its 
own  special  activity  of  science 

Starting  with  the  general  outlook  appropriate  to  science, 
philosophers  have  generally  made  Reality  their  substantive 
notion,  while  Value  has  become  adjectival.  It  is  quite  true 
that  Plato  spoke  of  the  Idea  of  Good  as  eVe/ee«/a  TT}?  overlap 
—which  the  context  proves  to  mean  "  above  and  beyond 
objective  being"  (Republic,  VI.,  509  b)  ;  but  he  does  not  follow 
this  up  by  including  ethics  and  politics  in  his  propaedeutic 
studies ;  he  remains  under  the  predominant  influence  of 
geometry.  So  S.  Thomas  Aquinas  is  quite  thorough  in  the 
deliberate  and  reiterated  identification  of  Good  with  Being — 
Bonum  et  ens  sunt  idem  secundum  rem:  sed  differunt  secun- 
dum  rationem  tantum  (Sum.  Theol.,  Pt.  L,  Q.  V.,  A.  I.) — yet 
he  goes  on  to  treat  Being  as  prior  because  it  is  the  first 
object  of  the  intellect,  and  thereafter  the  whole  concept  of 
Value  almost  disappears.  Consequently  his  definition  of 
Substance  as  that  which  exists  of  itself — substantial  nomen 
.  .  .  significant  essentiam  cui  competit  sic  esse,  idest  per  se 
esse  (Sum.  TheoL,  Pt.  I.,  Q.  Ill,  A.  V.) — never  leads  him 
even  to  consider  whether  this  is  not  the  same  as  to  say  that 
Substance  and  Good  (or  Value)  are  synonymous  terms  :  hence 
the  chief  difficulties  of  his  sacramental  theories. 

But  the   identity  of   substance  (so   defined)   with  Value 


474  WILLIAM   TEMPLE  I 

follows  inevitably  from  a  thorough-going  acceptance  of  the 
Theistic  hypothesis.  The  Universe  is  to  be  conceived  as 
deriving  its  origin  and  unity  from  a  Creative  Will.  But  the 
correlative  of  Will  is  Good  or  Value;  therefore  the  most 
fundamental  element  in  things  is  their  Value.  This  is  not 
a  property  which  they  have  incidentally  ;  it  is  the  constitutive 
principle,  the  true  self,  of  every  existent.  Aquinas  says- 
that  a  thing  is  perfect  in  so  far  as  it  exists :  Intantum  est 
autem  perfectum  unumquodque  inquantum  est  in  actu  (Sum. 
Theol.,  Q.  V.,  A.  I.) — and  that  everything  is  good  so  far  as 
it  exists:  Omne  ens,  inquantum  est  ens,  est  bonum  (Sum. 
Theol ,  Q.  V.,  A.  III.).  The  inversion  of  this  is  the  fertile 
truth:  everything  exists  so  far  as  it  is  good.  Value  and 
value  alone  is  substance  or  has  substantial  reality. 

IV. 

It  is  certainly  true  that  Value  is  only  actual  in  the  various 
things  that  are  valuable :  and  it  is  only  fully  actual  (though 
this  is  of  no  consequence  for  our  present  purpose)  so  far 
as  it  is  appreciated  by  some  conscious  being.  And  it  is 
tempting  to  separate  the  Good  from  the  good  thing,  and  to 
demand  either  some  account  of  it  in  such  separation  or  else 
a  method  of  apprehending  it  in  separation.  But  to  do  this 
is  to  repeat  the  mistake  made  by  the  Hedonists  in  Ethics. 
When  I  am  hungry,  I  want  food  and  not  (except  incidentally) 
the  pleasure  of  eating.  Desire  is  not  of  some  one  thing,  such 
as  pleasure.  And  yet  it  is  true  that  when  I  am  hungry  what 
I  want  is  the  value  or  the  good  of  food  ;  but  this  is  not  separ- 
able from  the  food,  and  is  not  even  properly  distinguishable 
from  it,  though  it  is  distinguishable  from  other  aspects  of 
the  particular  food  in  question  which  are  irrelevant  to  my 
hunger. 

So  Will  aims  at  Good  in  all  its  forms ;  and  as  God  makes 
the  world,  He  beholds  it  as  very  good.  There  is  the  problem 
of  Evil  of  course,  and  it  may  be  that  it  will  wreck  this  whole 
fashion  of  philosophy ;  but  we  cannot  embark  upon  the  dis- 
cussion of  it  here — I  can  only  refer  to  an  attempt  to  handle 
it  in  my  book  Mens  Creatrix.  Our  concern  just  now  is  with 
the  method  which  philosophy  must  pursue  if  it  adopts  this 
principle  that  only  Value  has  substantial  being. 

It  is  clear  at  once  that  Ethics  and  Politics,  and  ,ZEsthetics, 
will  be  exalted  alongside  of  Mathematics,  as  the  typical 
activities  of  Mind,  and  that  on  the  whole  they  will  be  the 
more  normative  for  Metaphysic.  The  Universe  will  be  ap- 
proached less  as  a  problem  (or  theorem)  in  Geometry,  more 


SYMBOLISM  AS  A  METAPHYSICAL   PEINCIPLE.  475 

as  a  Drama  or  Symphony,  and  as  a  Society  in  process  of 
formation. 

Now  if  the  structure  of  Keality  is  such  as  we  described, 
and  if  the  problem  of  Metaphysics  is  to  be  approached  along 
the  lines  now  indicated,  we  begin  to  see  a  great  unification 
take  place.  The  lower  grades,  we  said,  only  attain  to  the 
fulness  of  their  own  being  so  far  as  they  are  indwelt  and 
dominated  by  those  above  them.  They  exist  then,  ultimately, 
to  embody  or  symbolise  what  is  more  than  themselves.  The 
universe  is  sacramental.  Everything  except  the  Creative 
Will  exists  to  be  the  expression  of  that  Will,  the  actualisation 
of  its  values,  and  the  communication  of  those  Values  to 
spirits  created  for  the  special  value  actualised  through  fellow- 
ship in  creation  and  appreciation  of  values.  Men  can  do 
some  of  this  work  themselves.  Speech  is  a  manipulation  of 
sounds  for  just  such  communication  and  fellowship.  By 
this  doctrine  the  reality  of  the  objects  in  the  world  is  not 
divorced  from  our  sense  of  their  significance.  A  friend  gave 
me  during  the  war  an  illustration  to  show  how  familiar  a 
fact  is  the  transvaluation,  which  on  this  theory  is  the  only 
true  transubstantiation :  Suppose  a  man  comes  to  see  me, 
finds  some  strips  of  coloured  calico  on  the  floor,  and  amuses 
himself  by  dancing  on  them  to  show  his  contempt  for  what  he 
takes  to  be  my  interests ;  I  may  think  him  a  tiresome  fellow, 
but  that  will  be  all :  now  suppose  those  bits  of  calico  have 
been  sewn  together  to  make  my  national  flag,  and  he  dances 
contemptuously  on  it ;  I  shall  kick  him  out  of  the  house. 

That  is  comparatively  a  trifling  instance.  In  any  case  the 
symbolism  of  a  flag  is  purely  conventional.  Yet  even  here 
it  seems  absurd  to  say  that  the  reality  of  the  flag  is  the 
same  as  the  reality  of  the  strips  of  calico.  The  accidents  (as 
the  schoolmen  would  say)  are  the  same ;  the  substance  is 
changed. 

Beginning  with  such  a  conventional  symbol  we  may  go  on 
to  fuller  symbolism  such  as  that  of  great  Art.  Here  the 
principle  emerges  that  to  be  a  true  or  (as  I  have  named  it 
elsewhere)  an  essential  symbol,  a  thing  must  be  itself  an 
individual  instance  of  what  it  symbolises.  So  Othello  can 
symbolise  jealousy  because  he  is  a  very  individual  jealous 
man.  In  great  art,  at  least,  the  symbol  is  unique,  and  there 
is  no  other  way  of  saying  what  the  artist  has  said.  In 
Emerson's  great  phrase  "  The  word  is  one  with  that  it  tells 
of ".  If  after  reading  King  Lear  or  hearing  the  Fifth 
Symphony  a  man  asks  what  either  means,  we  can  only  tell 
him  that  each  means  itself ;  but  that  is  the  extreme  opposite 
of  saying  that  either  is  meaningless. 


476  WILLIAM  TEMPLE  ; 

In  that  highest  sphere  of  creative  art  which  we  call  human 
conduct,  the  good  or  value  sought  is  that  of  Personality  (or 
Character)  in  Fellowship,  with  all  the  varieties  that 'this 
implies.  Actions  have  their  value  as  symbolising  and  as  pro- 
ducing this. 

It  is  clear  that  as  we  advance  from  the  purely  conventional 
symbolism,  represented  by  the  flag,  to  the  essential  symbol 
of  great  art  or  of  ethical  conduct,  the  subjective  element  is 
reduced  in  importance,  at  least  so  far  as  it  is  variable.  The 
Union  Jack  has  value  only  for  those  who  are  familiar  with  a 
particular  convention ;  and  to  those  who  do  know  this  it 
may  have  very  different  values — for  Lord  Carson  and  Mr.  de 
Valera,  for  example.  Yefc  even  here  the  value  is  constitutive 
in  so  far  as  the  flag  is  only  made  for  the  sake  of  the  value. 
But  in  the  symbolism  of  Art  and  Conduct  there  is  no  such 
variability.  Men  may  still  react  in  varying  degrees  of 
intensity  to  the  different  embodiments  of  value;  some  are 
more  stirred  by  colour ;  some  more  by  line ;  some  are  more 
stirred  by  heroic  energy,  some  more  by  patient  humility. 
But  at  this  level  there  is  no  doubt  what  is  the  value  ex- 
pressed in  the  work  of  art  or  the  moral  action. 

If  we  start  with  this  principle  of  symbolism  as  our  basis, 
we  shall  not,  I  think,  be  led  to  any  system  very  different  in 
its  structure  from  such  as  is  set  out,  for  example,  by  Prof. 
Pringle-Pattison.  The  difference  will  be  mainly  one  of 
emphasis  and  of  detailed  expression;  but  difference  of  this 
kind  will  be  all-pervasive.  In  ways  innumerable  the  state- 
ment will  be  (as  I  think)  more  luminous  in  detail,  more 
sympathetic.  There  will  be  more  understanding  of  the 
different  phases  of  Eeality  from  the  inside.  For  it  is  the 
characteristic  of  aesthetic  and  moral  appreciation  that  in 
them  we  become  absorbed  in  the  object  itself,  as  a  single 
whole,  and  understand  it  by  letting  it  take  possession  of  us, 
whereas  in  science  we  understand  partly  by  setting  the 
object  in  an  ever- widening  context  and  learning  what  forces 
mould  it  from  without,  and  partly  by  breaking  it  up  analyti- 
cally into  its  own  constitutent  elements.  Of  course  our 
method  will  not  dispense  with  the  processes  and  results  of 
science ;  but  it  will  depend  quite  equally,  or  rather  more,  on 
those  of  art  and  morality.  We  shall  not  dispense  with  the 
psychologist  or  sociologist ;  but  we  shall  expect  to  learn  still 
more  of  philosophic  value  from  the  dramatist  and  the  states- 
man. We  shall  still  seek  rational  coherence,  but  shall 
interpret  it  more  as  realised  in  the  Civitas  Dei  than  as  repre- 
sented by  the  solution  of  logical  contradiction. 

Above  all  we  shall  avoid  two  difficulties  that  are  inherent 


SYMBOLISM   AS  A   METAPHYSICAL  PEINCIPLE.  477 

in  the  other  method.  We  shall  not  try  to  treat  the  merely 
physical  as  self-subsistent,  leaving  values  to  attach  themselves 
to  it  in  a  rather  vague  manner,  while  still  declaring  that  the 
explanation  of  the  lower  is  in  the  higher ;  but  making  this 
declaration,  we  shall  insist  that  the  higher  are  the  more  nearly 
self-subsisting,  while  only  the  Highest  is  altogether  so.  And 
we  shall  not  leave  God  to  hover  uncertainly  between  His 
function  as  the  universal  ground  of  existence  and  His  ad- 
jectival attachment  to  the  universe  as  the  sum  or  realisation 
of  its  values,  but  we  shall  confidently  affirm  Him  as  the  sole 
self-subsistent  Being,  existing  in  absolute  independence  of  all 
else,  for  whose  pleasure  and  by  whose  creative  activity  all 
things  are  and  were  created. 


V.— DISCUSSIONS. 
PHYSICS  AND  PERCEPTION. 

MY  purpose  in  what  follows  is  to  deal  with  certain  questions  raised 
by  Mr.  C.  A.  Strong  in  his  article  on  my  theory  of  the  external  world 
(MiND,  July,  1922).  Mr.  Strong  finds  difficulties  in  certain  points 
of  my  theory  of  perception,  which  are  really  points  in  my  theory  of 
physics.  The  main  purpose  of  this  whole  outlook  is,  in  my  view, 
to  fit  our  perceptions  into  a  physical  context,  and  to  show  how  they 
might,  with  sufficient  knowledge,  become  part  of  physics.  I  think 
the  questions  at  issue  between  Mr.  Strong  and  me  all  concern 
matter  rather  than  anything  psychological ;  I  shall  therefore  begin 
by  treating  the  topics  to  be  discussed  purely  from  the  point  of  view 
of  physics. 

Mr.  Strong  is  surprised  (p.  309)  that  I  should  suppose  particu- 
lars which  are  members  of  different  pieces  of  matter  to  exist  all  at 
the  same  place,  in  case  the  place  is  one  reached  by  light  from  all 
these  different  pieces  of  matter.  He  is  also  surprised  (p.  310)  that 
objects  are  "  apparently  everywhere  except  in  the  place  where  we 
see  and  feel  them,"  and  that  "  a  multitude  of  events,  all  happening 
after  12  o'clock,  should  be  the  constituents  of  an  event  happening 
at  12  o'clock  ".  He  points  out,  as  though  it  were  a  consequence 
I  had  not  observed,  that  "  the  object,  as  physical  science  conceives 
it,  is  not  correctly  defined  as  the  system  of  all  the  perspectives  .  .  . 
but  is  rather  their  mathematical  limit "  (p.  311). 

It  is  true  that  I  maintain  these  propositions  (to  which  I  shall 
return  presently),  and  it  is  true  that  they  are  somewhat  curious. 
But  the  curiousness  is  that  of  modern  physics,  for  which  I  am  not 
responsible.  (I  wish  I  were.)  A  piece  of  matter,  according  to 
modern  physics,  has  two  aspects,  one  gravitational,  the  other  electro- 
magnetic. (If  Weyl  is  right,  as  seems  highly  probable,  these  two 
aspects  can  be  reduced  to  one,  but  it  is  not  necessary  for  me  to  as- 
sume that  this  reduction  is  possible.)  Both  these  consist  of  a  field, 
extending  theoretically  throughout  space-time.  The  gravitational 
field  consists  in  a  certain  distortion  of  space-time,  making  it  every- 
where more  or  less  non-Euclidean,  but  particularly  so  in  a  certain 
neighbourhood,  the  neighbourhood  in  which  we  say  the  matter  is. 
The  electromagnetic  field  consists  of  "  something  "  (the  physicist 
cannot  say  more)  which  satisfies  Maxwell's  equations,  and  is  like- 
wise theoretically  diffused  throughout  space-time,  though  with  more 
intensity  in  a  certain  neighbourhood.  As  Einstein  puts  it : — 


BEETEAND  EUSSELL  :    PHYSICS   AND   PEECEPTION.        479 

"  Da  nach  unseren  heutigen  Auffassungen  auch  die  Elementar- 
teilchen  der  Materie  ihrem  Wesen  nach  nichts  anderes  sind  als 
Verdichtungen  des  elektromagnetischen  Feldes,  so  kennt  unser 
heutiges  Weltbild  zwei  begrifflich  volkommen  von  einander 
getrennte,  wenn  auch  kausal  aneinander  gebundene  Realitaten, 
namlich  Gravitationsaether  und  elektromagnetisches  Feld  oder — 
wie  man  sie  auch  nennen  konnte — Kaum  und  Materie."  l 

In  every  little  region  of  space-time,  according  to  this  view,  there 
are  two  things  to  be  considered  :  first,  the  metrical  structure  of  the 
neighbourhood,  which  represents  gravitation,  and  can  be  analysed 
into  a  number  of  superposed  gravitational  fields,  each  with  a  centre, 
which  may  be  taken  to  be  an  electron  ;  secondly,  the  electromag- 
netic field,  which  is  similarly  analysable.  There  are  thus  a  number 
of  things  happening  everywhere  always.  What  we  call  one 
element  of  matter — say  an  electron — is  represented  by  a  certain 
selection  of  the  things  that  happen  throughout  space-time,  or  at 
any  rate  throughout  a  large  region.  We  cannot  speak  in  any  ac- 
curate sense  of  the  "history"  of  a  piece  of  matter,  because  the 
time-order  of  events  is  to  a  certain  extent  arbitrary  and  dependent 
upon  the  reference-body.  Each  piece  of  matter  has,  however,  a 
"  proper  time,"  which  is  that  indicated  by  clocks  that  share  its 
motion ;  from  its  own  point  of  view,  this  proper  time  may  be  used 
to  define  its  history.  But  it  must  be  understood  that  a  piece  of 
matter  is  only  a  convenient  grouping  of  occurrences  which  extend 
throughout  space-time ;  it  is  these  occurrences,  not  matter,  that 
physics  accepts  as  ultimate. 

These  occurrences  are  ordered  in  a  four-dimensional  continuum 
called  space-time,  each  "point"  of  space-time  containing  many 
such  occurrences.  There  are  no  accurate  large-scale  metrical  re- 
lations between  occurrences  in  different  regions,  but  within  one 
small  neighbourhood  there  are  approximate  metrical  relations, 
which  are  more  or  less  non-Euclidean  according  to  the  gravitational 
field  in  the  neighbourhood.  All  ultimate  physical  relations  are 
embodied  in  differential  equations,  and  only  hold  accurately  in  the 
infinitesimal.  There  are  no  longer  such  things  as  straight  lines  of 
finite  length,  or  time-intervals  that  are  not  very  short.  That  is  to 
say,  all  relations  between  distant  occurrences,  even  those  that  we 
have  been  accustomed  to  regard  as  purely  geometrical  or  chrono- 
logical, proceed  by  propagation  through  the  intervening  region, 
like  light. 

It  is  into  a  physical  world  of  this  description  that  we  have  to  fit 
our  theory  of  perception. 

Before  proceeding  to  this  task,  there  is  a  philosophical  question 
to  be  disposed  of.  Mr.  Strong  says  : — 

"  Mr.  Russell  accepts  the  phenomenalistic  principle — as  we  may 
call  the  denial  of  the  legitimacy  of  transcendence — and  his  theory 
is,  in  the  main,  the  application  of  it  to  perception.  Does  he 

1  Aether  und  Relativitdtstheorie.  Rede  gehalten  am  5  Mai,  1920.  Ber- 
lin, Julius  Springer,  1920,  p.  14. 


480  BEETEAND  EUSSELL  : 

adhere  to  it  strictly  everywhere  ?  The  question  is  pertinent ;  for  a. 
principle  which  you  can  disregard  when  it  becomes  inconvenient 
is  perhaps  only  a  prejudice." 

I  have  never  called  myself  a  phenomenalist,  but  I  have  no  doubt 
sometimes  expressed  myself  as  though  this  were  my  view.  In  fact, 
however,  I  am  not  a  phenomenalist.  For  practical  purposes,  I 
accept  the  truth  of  physics,  and  depart  from  phenomenalism  so  far 
as  may  be  necessary  for  upholding  the  truth  of  physics.  I  do  not, 
of  course,  hold  that  physics  is  certainly  true,  but  only  that  it  has 
a  better  chance  of  being  true  than  philosophy  has.  Having  ac- 
cepted the  truth  of  physics,  I  try  to  discover  the  minimum  of 
assumptions  required  for  its  truth,  and  to  come  as  near  to  phen- 
omenalism as  I  can.  But  I  do  not  in  the  least  accept  the  phen- 
omenalist philosophy  as  necessarily  right,  nor  do  I  think  that  its 
supporters  always  realise  what  a  radical  destruction  of  ordinary 
beliefs  it  involves. 

I  will  try  to  make  more  explicit  my  attitude  on  this  question, 
Mr.  Strong  says :  "  You  cannot  go  beyond  your  own  sensations,  or 
the  world  as  they  present  it  to  you  "  (p.  312).  This  position  is  not 
maintained  by  Mr.  Strong  on  idealist  grounds,  but  on  grounds  of 
straightforward  theory  of  knowledge.  His  position  is,  I  suppose, 
that  we  have  immediate  knowledge  of  our  sensations,  but  that  this 
knowledge  is  not  of  a  sort  to  enable  us  to  infer  anything  other  than 
our  own  sensations.  I  should  reply  :  (1)  that  we  do  not  immedi- 
ately know  either  our  own  sensations  or  anything  else ;  (2)  that  no 
atomic  fact  can  ever  be  demonstratively  inferred  from  any  other 
atomic  fact ;  (3)  that,  assuming  the  validity  of  induction  and  analogy 
(on  the  lines  set  forth  by  Mr.  Keynes),  it  is  possible  to  make 
probable  inferences  from  one  fact  to  another ;  (4)  that  in  such 
inferences  the  inferred  probable  fact  need  not  lie  within  our  ex- 
perience or  anyone  else's  ;  (5)  that  philosophy  has  immensely  over- 
estimated the  importance  of  knowledge,  which  is  merely  a  phy- 
sical relation  between  physical  occurrences,  or  at  any  rate  does  not 
differ  from  this  in  any  important  way. 

(1)  The  question  of  "  immediate  knowledge  "  can  only  be  treated 
historically  ;  it  only  arises  when  we  have  reached  the  stage  of 
Cartesian  doubt.  At  this  stage,  we  find  ourselves  with  a  system 
of  beliefs  as  a  going  concern,  and  it  strikes  us  that  some  of  these 
beliefs  are  inferred,  while  others  are  not.  It  is  difficult  to  define 
what  is  meant  by  an  "  inferred"  belief.  When,  for  example,  you 
see  a  tree  beginning  to  fall,  you  expect  to  hear  a  crash ;  but  this 
belief  as  to  the  future  has  not  been  inferred  by  a  logical  process. 
It  is,  however,  derivative  from  what  you  see  ;  if  your  belief  were 
challenged,  you  could  allege  what  you  see  in  justification.  All 
beliefs  which  are  in  this  wide  sense  derivative  come  within  the 
scope  of  Cartesian  doubt,  unless  some  logical  process  can  be  found 
by  which  they  might  have  been  inferred  from  beliefs  which  are  in 
no  sense  derivative,  or  at  any  rate  not  derivative  from  other  beliefs. 
When  we  start  to  look  for  beliefs  which  are  not  derivative,  we  find, 


PHYSICS  AND   PEECEPTION.  481 

at  first  sight,  three  kinds :  perceptions,  memories,  and  logical 
principles.  To  begin  with  the  last :  I  suspect  that  logical  principles 
are  really  always  propositions  about  symbols,  and  are  derivative 
from  perceptions  of  geometrical  (or  quasi-geometrical)  relations 
among  symbols.  That  is  to  say  :  a  logical  principle  never  asserts 
that  this  can  be  inferred  from  that,  but  only  that  this  symbol  and 
that  have  the  same  meaning ;  the  assertion  that  two  symbols  have 
the  same  meaning  is  based  upon  a  relation  between  their  forms.1 
It  would  take  me  too  far  from  my  theme  to  dwell  further  upon  this 
question.  As  for  memories,  it  might  be  thought  odd  to  include 
them  among  non-derivative  beliefs.  I  do  not  think  one  would 
naturally  include  them  in  the  usual  case,  where  what  is  remembered 
was  perceived  when  it  happened ;  but  when,  as  sometimes  occurs, 
we  remember  something  which  we  did  not  notice  at  the  time,  it 
seems  as  if  the  remembrance  had  the  same  claim  to  be  regarded  as 
non-derivative  as  a  perception  would  have.  This  brings  us  to 
perceptions.  Mr.  Strong  does  not  discuss  my  analysis  of  percep- 
tion, which,  so  far  as  I  know,  is  orthodox ;  I  assume  that  he  does 
not  seriously  disagree  with  it.  Thus  a  perception  consists  of  two 
parts  :  (a)  a  core  of  sensation ;  (b)  images  and  beliefs  called  up  by 
the  sensation  through  the  influence  of  past  experience.  The  second 
part  is  derivative  in  an  important  sense,  and  must  certainly  be  in- 
cluded within  the  scope  of  Cartesian  doubt,  since  the  beliefs  which 
enter  into  it  are  sometimes  erroneous.  The  first  part  does  not 
consist  of  beliefs,  but  is  a  mere  occurrence,  of  just  that  kind  with 
which  physics  is  concerned  and  by  which  its  theories  are  empirically 
tested.  Moreover,  it  is  a  difficult  question  of  theory  to  discover 
the  sensational  core  in  a  perception,  and  it  is  highly  doubtful 
whether  it  can  be  distinguished  from  the  accompanying  images 
except  by  assuming  an  external  world  with  which  it  is  correlated 
in  a  way  that  images  do  not  exactly  share.  We  are  thus  left  with 
nothing  immediate  except  the  core  of  sensation,  which  is  not 
knowledge,  and  is  not  itself  immediately  known. 

(2)  That  no  atomic  fact  can  ever  be  demonstratively  inferred 
from  any  other  atomic  fact  is  again  a  view  which  I  have  taken  from 
Mr.  Wittgenstein ;  it  obviously  hangs  together  with  his  view  of 
logical  principles.     It  is  of  course  a  view  at  least  as  old  as  Hume. 
I  do  not  see  how  anyone  can  dispute  it  who  examines  the  nature 
of  logical  inference.     I  do  not  mean  to  deny  that  from  the  fact  that 
two  propositions  are  true  we  can  infer  that  each  of  them  severally 
is  true,  nor  do  I  mean  to  deny  the  validity  of  Barbara.     But  such 
methods  do  not  give  new  knowledge,  and  I  do  not  see  how  the 
methods  of  demonstrative  logic  can  ever  do  so.     An  "  atomic " 
fact  is  one  which  does  not  consist  of  two  or  more  facts ;  it  is  im- 
plied that  it  is  not  general. 

(3)  On  the   question  of   probable  inferences   by  induction  and 
analogy,  I  am  prepared  for  the  moment  to  accept  what  Mr.  Keynes 

1 1  have   adopted  this   view   from  Mr.  Wittgenstein.      See  his  forth- 
coming work  on  Philosophical  Logic  (Kegan  Paul). 

31 


482  BEKTEAND  EUSSELL  : 

has  to  say,  though  I  have  no  doubt  that  he  has  only  laid  down  the 
broad  lines  of  a  theory  which  can  be  amplified.  I  assume  in 
practice  the  validity  of  inductive  methods  as  they  occur  in  science, 
although  I  do  not  think  that  the  results  obtained  are  certain.  In 
many  cases  they  are  far  from  certainty,  but  no  other  method  will 
lead  to  results  having  a  higher  degree  of  probability.  It  is  because 
of  the  absence  of  certainty  that  it  is  desirable  to  organise  and  in- 
terpret science  in  the  way  involving  fewest  assumptions ;  this  is 
the  reason  why,  in  practice,  I  approach  as  near  to  phenomenalism 
as  I  can  without  destroying  the  whole  edifice  of  science.  What  is 
involved  is  not  an  absolute  philosophical  principle,  but  a  method  of 
securing  a  higher  degree  of  probability. 

(4)  When  inferences  are  made  by  analogy  and  induction,  what 
is  inferred  need  not  lie  within  our  experience  or  anyone  else's.    It 
is  clear,  in  the  first  place,  that  we  only  employ  such  inferences  when 
what  we  infer  does  not  lie  within  our  present  or  remembered  ex- 
perience.    We  therefore  habitually  assume  that  they  are  valid  as 
applied  to  future  experience.     If  so,  what  can  prevent  them  from 
being  valid  as  applied  to  something  not  experienced  at  all  ?    There 
is  of  course  the  idealist  position,  according  to  which  it  is  logically 
impossible  for  anything  to  exist  without  being  experienced;  but 
this,  I  gather,  is  not  Mr.  Strong's  position.    His  view  is  merely  that 
there  can  be  no  valid  inductive  inference  from  what  has  been  ex- 
perienced to  what  will  never  be  experienced.     I  do  not  know  how 
he  would  justify  this  view.     Of  course  it  is  true  that  what  is  not 
experienced  cannot  be  directly  verified,  but  it  can  form  part  of  a 
body  of  hypothesis  of  which  other  parts  can  be  verified.    It  is  natural 
to  suppose  that  Neptune  existed  before  it  was  discovered.     If  you 
see  your  cat  running  away  with  a  fish  which  was  in  your  larder,  it 
is  natural  to  suppose  that  the  cat  has  been  in  the  larder.     Such  in- 
ferences transcend  experience  in  the  way  which  Mr.  Strong  regards 
as  illegitimate ;  but  I  do  not  see  in  what  respect  they  fail  to  con- 
form to  the  canons  of  inductive  inference. 

(5)  Since  Kant — perhaps  since  Hume — philosophy  seems  to  me 
to  have   overemphasised  the   importance  of  knowledge,  and  the 
difference  between  what  we  know  and  what  we  do  not  know.    Per- 
haps the  trouble  goes  further  back,  to  the  Cartesian  emphasis  on  the 
difference  between  mind  and  matter.     It  is  clear  that  Mr.  Strong 
regards  our  visual  perceptions  as  something  very  different  from 
what  physics  treats  as  light,  and  that  his  reluctance  to  infer  beyond 
experience  is  bound  up  with  this  belief  that,  if  there  is  anything 
beyond  experience,  it  must  be  very  unlike  sensations.     I  believe 
this  to  be  a  mistake.     To  my  mind,  the  world  is  full  of  particulars 
of  the  sort  dealt  with  by  physics,  and  some  of  these  particulars 
(namely  those  in  places  where,  as  we  say,  there  is  a  brain)  have 
peculiar  effects  which  are  called  "  being  known  "  or  "  being  ex- 
perienced "  .    I  think  that  particulars  (of  which  there  are  many  in 
one  "  point  "  of  space-time)  can  be  collected  into  sets  of  such  a  sort 
that  two  neighbouring  members  of  the  same  set  differ  very  little. 


PHYSICS  AND   PEECEPTION.  483 

I  think  that  when  I  see  (say)  a  penny,  what  I  perceive  is  one 
member  of  the  system  which  is  the  momentary  penny,  and  that  it 
is  that  member  which  is  situated  (according  to  one  meaning  of 
"  situation  ")  in  a  certain  part  of  my  brain.  I  think  that,  very  near 
this  part  of  the  brain,  there  are  closely  similar  unperceived  par- 
ticulars which  are  other  members  of  the  momentary  penny ;  there 
is  no  solution  of  continuity  in  passing  from  what  I  perceive  to  the 
outside  particulars  dealt  with  by  physics. 

If  this  view  is  correct,  a  mental  occurrence  is  to  be  called  a 
"perception"  when  it  has  a  certain  kind  of  relation,  based  upon 
certain  differential  laws  of  change  (those  of  perspective,  to  the  first 
order),  to  a  number  of  other  occurrences  all  linked  with  each  other 
in  the  same  way.  Common  sense  imagines  that  there  is  a  "  thing  " 
which  "  causes  "  all  these  occurrences,  but  that  is  an  unnecessary 
hypothesis,  which  is  avoided  by  defining  the  "thing"  as  the  group 
of  these  occurrences.  Thus  a  "  perception  "  is  a  member  of  a  thing 
occurring  in  a  place  where  there  are  mnemic  effects,  and  it  is  these 
mnemic  effects  which  give  rise  to  what  is  called  knowledge  of  the 
thing. 

Why  should  such  a  theory  be  thought  probable?  (I  do  not 
claim  that  it  is  more  than  probable.)  (a)  Because  it  harmon- 
ises physics,  the  physiology  of  the  sense-organs,  and  psychology. 
(b)  Because  it  fits  perception  into  that  correlation  by  differential 
equations  to  which  all  physical  laws  have  been  reduced,  and 
avoids  treating  perception  as  a  case  of  action  at  a  distance  ;  in  other 
words,  because  it  is  in  harmony  with  the  principle  of  continuity, 
which,  though  not  logically  necessary,  has  been  found  increasingly 
fruitful  in  science.  (Continuity  here  is  not  to  be  understood  in  a 
strict  sense,  but  only  in  an  approximate  sense.  In  its  strict  sense 
it  is  incompatible  with  the  theory  of  quanta,  and  very  likely  false.) 

My  view  of  the  relation  of  what  we  perceive  to  physics  is  the 
same  as  that  of  Dr.  Whitehead,  who  first  persuaded  me  to  adopt  it. 
I  do  not  think  that  he  would  agree  with  my  psychology  in  other 
respects,  but  in  this  matter  the  view  set  forth  in  his  two  books  is 
practically  the  same  as  that  which  I  am  advocating.  He  holds,  as 
I  do,  that  colours  and  sounds  and  secondary  qualities  generally 
should  not  be  extruded  from  the  physical  world.  The  habit  of 
shutting  them  out  he  calls  the  "  bifurcation  of  nature  ".  But  he 
still  allows  a  bifurcation  between  nature  and  mind,  perhaps  only 
because  he  deliberately  excludes  mind  from  his  theme.  I  wish  to 
include  nature  and  mind  in  one  single  system,  in  a  science  which 
will  be  very  like  modern  physics,  though  not  at  all  like  the 
materialistic  billiard-ball  physics  of  the  past.  A  great  deal  of  work 
will  be  required  to  show  in  detail  how  the  data  of  sense  are  to  be 
fitted  into  physics.  What  Dr.  Whitehead  and  I  have  done  so  far 
is  only  a  small  part  of  the  necessary  work,  which  probably  neither 
he  nor  I  will  be  able  to  complete.  I  only  want,  as  yet,  to  re- 
commend the  general  point  of  view  as  a  possible  one,  which  de- 
serves to  be  worked  out. 


484  BEBTEAND   EUSSELL  : 

I  will  end  with  a  discussion  of  some  special  points  raised  by  Mr. 
Strong.  On  page  309,  he  objects  to  the  theory  that,  at  a  place  from 
which  a  number  of  objects  are  visible,  perspectives  of  all  of  them 
exist,  on  the  ground  that  there  is  need  of  a  lens  to  separate  out  the 
different  light-rays.  He  admits,  however,  that  "  the  perspectives  can 
by  analysis  be  separated  out,"  and  that  is  quite  enough  for  me.  You 
cannot  by  analysis  separate  out  what  was  not  there.  He  argues 
that,  apart  from  something  like  a  lens,  "  what  exists  there  is  only 
a  synthesis  of  effects,  and  not  anything  like  the  stars  from  which 
the  rays  proceeded".  Up  to  a  point,  this  is  true,  and  it  accounts 
for  the  vagueness  of  perception.  I  emphasised  this  point  in 
Analysis  of  Mind,  pp.  135-136. 

Space  comes  next.  "  What  first  strikes  one  in  this  theory  is  the 
curious  reversal  of  the  spatial  position  of  objects  which  it  seems  to 
involve — objects  being  apparently  everywhere  except  in  the  place 
where  we  see  and  feel  them"  (Strong,  p.  310).  As  I  explained  in 
my  book  on  the  External  World  (which,  however,  laid  too  little 
stress  on  relativity),  we  have  to  start  with  a  private  space-time  for 
each  percipient,  and  generally  for  each  piece  of  matter.  The  cor- 
relation of  these  with  the  constructed  public  space-time  is  a  long 
piece  of  work,  but  obviously  feasible.  The  "  place  where  a  par- 
ticular is  "  is  ambiguous ;  it  may  mean  the  place  where  it  is  in  its 
perspective,  or  the  place  where  it  is  in  the  system  which  is  the 
physical  thing  of  which  it  is  a  member,  or  the  place  where  this 
thing  is  in  public  space-time.  When  these  distinctions  are  borne 
in  mind,  Mr.  Strong's  paradox  disappears.  The  quotation  from 
Einstein  with  which  I  began  shows  that  my  view  is  in  harmony 
with  modern  physics. 

Mr.  Strong  next  objects  to  the  similar  paradox  as  regards  time, 
namely  that  the  moment  in  public  time  to  which  an  occurrence  is 
to  be  assigned  is  earlier  than  the  various  moments  in  public  time 
to  which  are  to  be  assigned  the  particulars  which  are  members  (or 
"  appearances  ")  of  the  occurrence  at  various  places.  The  answer 
here  is  essentially  the  same  as  before.  Public  time  is  a  convention, 
which  may  be  fixed  in  many  equally  legitimate  ways ;  it  may 
happen  that  A  is  before  B  according  to  one  legitimate  convention, 
while  according  to  another  B  is  before  A.  All  this  is  already  in  the 
special  theory  of  relativity.  One  need  not  therefore  treat  the  time- 
order  of  events  with  any  undue  respect. 

One  more  point :  "  We  may  draw  one  inference  from  these 
paradoxes,  and  that  is  that  the  object,  as  physical  science  con- 
ceives it,  is  not  correctly  defined  as  the  system  of  all  the  perspec- 
tives (even  of  the  'regular'  ones,  i.e.,  those  undistorted  by  the 
interviewing  medium),  but  is  rather  their  mathematical  limit " 
(Strong,  p.  311).  I  myself  suggested  this  view  in  my  book  on  the 
External  World,  but  rejected  it 'for  the  reason  that  there  is  no  limit 
to  which  the  appearances  approach.  For  this  reason,  in  Analysis 
of  Mind  (pp.  106-107),  I  defined  a  piece  of  matter  as  that  set  of 
appearances  to  which  the  set  approximates  which  consists  of  a 


PHYSICS   AND   PERCEPTION.  485 

given  appearance  together  with  all  those  others  which  would  exist 
if  the  given  appearance  were  regular.  This  is  a  limiting  set,  not  a 
limiting  single  appearance,  and  it  exists  when  the  limiting  single 
appearance  does  not.  The  device  is  essentially  the  same  as  that 
of  defining  an  irrational  number  as  a  certain  class  of  rationals. 
It  must  be  understood  that  a  "piece  of  matter"  is  not  anything 
real,  but  merely  some  constructed  object  having  properties  which 
enable  us  to  state  shortly  facts  or  laws  concerning  a  whole  set  of 
particulars  that  are  real.  In  defining  a  piece  of  matter,  therefore, 
we  are  to  be  guided  solely  by  convenience. 

There  are  other  points  in  Mr.  Strong's  article  which  I  should 
like  to  deal  with,  but  I  think  what  I  should  have  to  say  about  them 
can  be  inferred  by  the  reader  from  what  I  have  already  said.  I 
will,  therefore,  close  this  discussion,  which  is  already  long  enough, 
by  expressing  gratitude  to  Mr.  Strong  for  having  brought  into 
prominence  so  many  important  points. 

BERTRAND  BUSSELL. 


REJOINDER. 

WITH  all  respect  to  Mr.  Russell,  I  doubt  whether  molecular  physics 
and  the  Einstein  theory  are  relevant  to  the  question.  Perception 
on  its  physical  side  is  a  relation  of  the  large-scale  sort,  like  that 
by  which  an  animal  seeks  food  and  avoids  danger,  is  not  injured 
by  poisons  that  are  outside  his  body,  does  not  hear  a  sound  that  is 
too  far  away  or  too  faint,  and  does  not  see  in  the  dark,  despite  the 
emanations  from  objects.  In  short,  there  is  a  clear  distinction 
between  the  organism  and  its  environment,  and  Mr.  Russell  must 
not  use  relativity  to  undermine  the  foundations  of  biology. 

I  agree  with  him  in  more  respects  than  he,  through  having 
misread  (the  fault,  I  am  sure,  is  mine)  a  sentence  that  was  meant 
ironically,  imagines.  I  do  not  deny  that  we  can  "  go  beyond  our 
sensations" — on  the  contrary,  that  is  just  what  I  assert,  against 
Mr.  Russell  (when  he  says  that  the  thing  of  common  sense  is  "an 
unnecessary  hypothesis  ").  But  I  agree  with  him  that  a  sensation 
is  not  intrinsically  self-transcendent  or  knowing,  and  that  it  is  not 
immediately  known ;  I  agree  with  him  that  perception  rests  on  a 
purely  physical  relation ;  and  my  aim,  like  his,  is  to  bring  nature 
and  the  self  together  into  one  single  science  which  shall  be  like 
physics.  But  I  do  not  believe  that  perception  is  a  purely  physical 
relation — I  believe  that  it  is  one  of  significance  ;  and  (here  I  come 
to  the  vital  issue  between  us)  I  hold  that  the  "  core  of  sensation  " 
— quite  apart  from  the  images — serves  as  the  sign  of,  and  is  the 
part  of  the  self  that  enables  us  to  know,  what  Mr.  Russell  would 
call  the  rest  of  the  object  outside  the  body,  and  what  I  call  the 
object. 

(1)  Though  objects  consist  of  groups  of  electrons,  it  is  not  the 
mere  radiations  of  the  electrons  that  enable  us  to  perceive.  In  the 
first  place  these  radiations,  after  they  reach  the  brain,  are  not  a 
part  of  the  object,  and  it  is  a  misuse  of  language  to  say  that  a  table, 
when  I  see  it,  is  partly  in  my  brain,  or  that  a  star  which  has  been 
extinguished,  but  rays  of  light  from  which  continue  to  reach  my 
eyes,  still  partly  exists.  Yet  this  is  the  device  by  which  Mr.  Russell 
and  Mr.  Whitehead  would  satisfy  common  sense,  and  include 
colours  and  other  secondary  qualities  in  the  object.  In  the  second 
place  Mr.  Russell  (fortunately  for  him)  recognises  that  the  sensation 
is  tied  to  and  varies  with  the  brain,  and  this  recognition  (unusual, 
I  think,  with  neo-realists)  has  put  him  in  a  difficult  position.  If 
he  would  not  admit  the 
miracle  at  all),  he  must  (: 


'  miracle  of  knowing '   (which  is  not  a 
in  his  physics,   not  in  his  philosophy) 


c.  A.  STRONG:  EEJOINDEE.  487 

bring  the  object  bodily  into  the  brain.  In  truth,  an  object  perceived 
is  no  more  in  the  brain  than  one  seen  in  a  mirror  is  really  in  the 
mirror — in  fact  the  one  kind  of  in-being  is  exactly  like  the  other. 

(2)  Mr.  Eussell  has  slipped  too  easily  out  of  my  difficulty  about 
the  lens.     The  intra-cerebral  effects  due  to   radiations   from    an 
object,  like  the  image  on  the  retina,  form  a  '  perspective '  (if  you 
mean  by  that  a  flat  picture,  or  something  whose  hitherward  end  is 
a  flat  picture) ;  but  they  do  so  because  the  parts  of  the  brain-process 
are  arranged  in  the  same  way  as  the  parts  of  the  object,  and  this  is 
impossible  without  a  lens.     The  radiations  outside  the  body  have 
no  perspective  form ;  they  are  mere  effects,  and  effects  lost  in  a 
synthesis  with  other  effects ;  to  say  that  they  are  perspectives  is  as 
if  you  said  that  a  block  of  marble  consists  of  statues.     Thus  Mr. 
Russell's  plan  for  securing  the  continued  existence,  I  do  not  say  of 
objects  (for  the  effects  do  exist  continuously),  but  of  '  perspectives/ 
comes  to  naught.     There  are  no  actual  perspectives  except  when 
some  one  perceives. 

(3)  It  follows  from  this  that  there  can  be  only  one  perspective 
in  the  brain  at  a  time.     This  perspective  is  not  lodged  in  a  point, 
but  in  an  extended  field,  an  area.     It  is  not  true,  then,  that  at  a 
neighbouring  point  in  the  brain  there  is  another  actual  perspective ; 
other  actual  perspectives  are  got,  not  by  moving  to  another  point 
in  the  brain,  but  by  moving  the  brain  to  another  point — exactly  as 
if  it  were  a  camera. 

(4)  Mr.  Russell's  perspectives  are  of  course  not  really  in  the 
brain — they  are  merely  dependent  upon  it ;  and  they  are  not  flat 
pictures  merely,  but  views.     Now  that  which  makes  the  difference 
between  a  flat  picture  and  such  a  view  (apart  from  the  physical 
character  of  the  one  and  the,  shall  we  say,  metaphysical  character 
of  the  other)  is  the  depth.     And  it  is  only  the  length  and  breadth 
in  the  perspective  that  are  immediately  tied  to  the  process  in  the 
brain  ;  the  depth  depends  on  the  adjustment  of  the  optical  muscles 
and  the  way  in  which  we  react.     Moreover,  I  think  it  is  a  fact  of 
observation  that  depth  is  not  sensible  in  the  same  way,  the  same 
visual  way,  that  length  and  breadth  are — depth  is  not  coloured. 
These  are  the  facts  that  seem  to  me  to  justify  the  view  that  the 
visual  sensation  has  only  length  and  breadth. 

(5)  A  lower  animal,  with  visual  sensations  but  whom  we  may 
suppose  to  be  without  images,  refers  the  sensation  to  the  outer 
object  by  the  way  in  which  he  reacts ;  and  reposes  in  the  reality  of 
the  object  something  which  we  may  call  instinctive  trust.     So  long 
as  he  does  that,  the  vision  of  the  object,  what  I  have  called  the 
view,  appears  to  him  ;  but  if  he  should  drop  his  outwardly  directed 
attitude,  he  would  be  left  with  the  mere  flat  picture,  the  sensation. 
But  suppose  he  should  say  to  himself — while  always  acting  as  if 
he  saw  something  external — that  theoretically,  and  as  a  matter  of 
economy  of  assumptions,  the  object  was  "  an  unnecessary  hypo- 
thesis "  :  he  would  now  have  remaining,  not  the  sensation,  but  the 
view  or  '  perspective  '. 


488  C.   A.    STEONG  :   EEJOINDEE. 

If,  now,  this  philosophic  animal  supposes  views  to  exist  when 
nobody  has  them,  and  to  be  as  numerous  as  physical  points,  he 
will  be  a  sort  of  neo-realist,  and  his  philosophy  may  be  described 
as  comminuted  Leibniz.  But  perspectives,  in  this  sense,  are  not 
as  numerous  as  physical  points,  they  are  only  as  numerous  as 
actual  brain  processes ;  they  do  not  exist  actually  when  no  one  is 
seeing,  but  only  as  possibilities;  and  perception  in  truth  is  a 
function  belonging  only  to  animals,  not,  as  Leibniz  thought,  to 
every  particle  of  matter.  If,  recognising  these  things,  our  phil- 
osopher contents  himself,  apart  from  his  own  actual  perspective, 
with  other  perspectives  that  are  mere  possibilities,  but  conceives 
the  perspective  as  something  that  is  at  once  an  appearance  and  a 
sensation,  a  view  and  a  picture,  his  '  perceptions  '  will  have  changed 
from  those  of  Leibniz  to  those  of  Hume.  If,  again,  he  clears  the 
appearance  of  its  confusion  with  the  sensation,  and  squarely  throws 
the  external  world  overboard,  interpreting  it  as  his  own  egoistic 
creation,  his  one  perspective  will  be  not  less  atomic,  but  it  will  be 
that  of  Fichte. 

But  suppose  he  recovers  some  measure  of  his  original  trust  in 
the  external — perhaps  through  the  consideration  that  other  people's 
sensations  are  outside  his  own.  Economy  would  now  dictate  that 
he  should  stop  short  with  sensations — I  mean  with  that  external 
thing  which  he  looks  back  at  when  he  apprehends  a  sensation. 
Since  it  is  at  least  certain  that  there  is  a  sensation  somehow  tied  to 
his  own  brain-process,  which  is  necessarily  external  to  the  mind  of 
an  anatomist  viewing  that  brain-process,  he  may  not  unnaturally 
conclude  that  what  the  anatomist  sees  is  the  sensation,  and  then, 
by  analogy,  that  so  perhaps  objects  and  events  external  to  himself 
are  in  their  inner  nature  sensations,  or  like  sensations :  and  the 
philosophy  that  results  will  be  that  of  Fechner  and  Clifford.  It 
seems  to  me  that  the  direction  in  which  Mr.  Eussell  and  his 
relativist  friends  are  tending  is  this  last.1 

C.  A.  STRONG. 

1  See  Eddington,  Space,  Time  and  Gravitation,  p.  192. 


SOME  REMARKS  ON  RELATIVITY. 

PEOBABLY,  by  now,  even  philosophers  have  had  enough  of  relativity, 
but  perhaps  a  few  remarks  on  Miss  Wrinch's  discussion  of  the 
Methodology  of  Relativity  (MiND,  April,  p.  200)  may  be  of  interest ; 
and  also  in  this  connexion  I  should  like  to  point  out — in  a  few 
words — what  seems  to  me  to  be  a  grievous  logical  error  in  the 
theory  of  relations  as  expounded  by  some  of  Einstein's  philosophical 
followers. 

As  Miss  Wrinch  points  out,  "  there  are  now  various  different 
views  of  the  characteristics  of  space"  (and  Time?)  "held  by 
different  writers  on  Relativity,"  but  "there  is  still  something  of 
fundamental. importance  in  their  treatment  of  the  notion  of  Space" 
(and  Time).  In  the  second  paragraph  of  her  article  this  common 
fundamental  point  is  expressed  by  saying  that  "  There  is  nothing 
in  the  External  World  to  which  we  can  point  as  being  represented 
by  the  symbol  for  space  ".  We  may  express  this  by  saying  that 
while  the  words  "  Space  "  and  "  Time  "  have  meaning,  they  do  not 
denote  objects.  According  to  the  Absolute  Theory,  however,  Space 
and  Time  are  real  existent  bodies  or  series  of  points  and  moments  ; 
physical  objects  are  related  to  Space  and  to  Time,  and  Space  and 
Time  are  related  to  physical  objects,  for  example  things  are  in 
Space,  or  occur  at  the  same  moment  and  so  on ;  and  in  general 
the  various  spatial  and  temporal  relations  contain  reference  to 
points  of  space  or  moments  of  time. 

With  the  Relative  theory  all  these  points  and  moments  are  swept 
away.  Spatial  and  temporal  relations  hold  directly  between 
physical  objects  and  their  full  and  complete  analysis  contains  no 
mention  of  points  of  Space  or  moments  of  Time  or  any  object 
that  might  be  called  Space  or  Time ;  in  the  analysis  of  spatial 
relations  Einstein  regards  Space  as  an  unperceived,  unreal  and  un- 
necessary tertium  quid.  With  this  theory,  propositions  like  '  a  is 
in  Time  '  simply  mean  '  a  is  before,  simultaneous  or  after  some- 
thing/ i.e.,  a  is  temporally  related,  '  b  is  in  Space '  means  '  b  is 
spatially  related  to  something'.  This  is  a  general  characteristic 
of  the  treatment  of  Space  and  Time  by  Einstein  and  his  followers 
and  I  think  it  is  the  one  to  which  Miss  Wrinch  wishes  to  draw  our 
attention,  but  I  demur  from  her  assertion  that — in  the  language  of 
Modern  Logic1 — "it  consists  in  using  Space  as  a  description". 

(a)  It  is  more  correct  to  say  that  it  consists  in  using  "  Space  " 

1  The  language  of  modern  logic  seems  at  the  moment  to  be  the  language 
of  the  Principia  Mathematica. 


490  B.   AINSCOUGH  : 

as  an  '  incomplete  symbol  '.  "  Incomplete  symbol  "  is  a  rather 
unhappy  phrase,  it  would  be  better  to  speak  of  "  disappearing 
symbols  ".  An  incomplete  symbol  may  be  denned  as  one  such 
that  if  it  occurs  in  the  common  expression  of  any  proposition  p  it 
does  not  occur  in  the  logical  analysis  of  p,  that  is  in  the  determinate 
and  logically  accurate  expression  of  p.1  Thus  an  incomplete 
symbol  appears  in  the  expression  of  ordinary  thought  and  even  in 
the  abbreviations  of  logic,  but  disappears  from  the  full  expression 
of  precise  and  accurate  thought.  And  this  is  exactly  what  happens 
to  the  symbols  "Space"  and  "Time"  in  the  formulations  of  the 
theories  of  relativity.  The  words  "  Space  "  and  "  Time  "  may 
occur  in  writings  about  the  theory  of  relativity  but  not  in  the 
precise  and  accurate  formulation  of  the  theory  itself. 

(b)  The  truth  about  "  Space  "  being  a  description  seems  clear. 
The  actual  word  "Space"  is  not  used  as  a  description  either  by 
the  supporters  of  the  Absolute  or  the  Relative  theory,  but  both 
parties  use  spatial  relations  as  descriptions  or  as  parts  of  descrip- 
tions. For  the  upholders  of  Absolute  space  the  word  "Space" 
denotes  a  real  object  or  set  of  points  and  for  their  opponents  the 
word  is  a  disappearing  symbol,  that  is  so  far  as  they  speak  with 
logical  precision  they  do  not  use  it  at  all.  But  spatial  relations,  — 
or  rather  the  symbols  expressing  spatial  relations,  are  used  as 
parts  of  descriptions  by  both  parties. 

Consider  the  examples  given  by  Miss  Wrinch.  "The  building 
on  my  right  is  loftier  than  that."  The  symbol  "  The  building  on 
my  right  "  is  a  description,  whatever  may  be  the  true  theory  of 
Space  or  the  true  nature  of  the  relation  '  To  the  right  of  '. 

Similarly  "  Equiangular  triangles  are  equilateral  "  is  a  proposi- 
tion analysable  into  the  form  — 


with  either  the  Relative  or  the  Absolute  theory. 

Henca  we  cannot  capture  the  distinctive  characteristic  of  the 
relative  theory  by  saying  that  it  uses  Space  or  spatial  relations  as 
descriptions. 

Perhaps  these  two  points  can  be  exemplified  and  made  clearer 
by  considering  the  last  two  sentences  of  Miss  Wrinch's  discussion  ; 
they  are  "  But  whichever  part  of  the  general  investigation  is  being 
undertaken,  not  in  the  case  of  any  one  of  them  is  it  significant  to 
ask  '  What  is  Space  '.  It  is  the  properties  and  not  the  intrinsic 
nature  of  space  which  is  the  subject  of  investigation." 

Discussing  the  latter  sentence  first,  it  should  be  rejected  for  the 
reason  that  any  investigation  of  the  predicates  of  an  object  involves 
an  investigation  of  its  qualities  and  this  is  the  same  as  an  investi- 
gation of  its  intrinsic  nature.  It  is  more  correct  to  say  that  with 
the  Theory  of  Relativity  the  subject  of  investigation  is  not  space 
or  time  but  the  spatial  and  temporal  properties  of  objects,  for  space 

1  This  at  least  is  the  sense  in  which  Russell  uses  it  when  he  speaks  of  a 
class  as  an  incomplete  symbol. 


SOME   EEMAEKS   ON  BELATIVITY.  491 

and  time  are  mere  symbols  which  disappear  when  we  speak  with 
logical  precision.  This  is  the  reason  why,  for  the  theory  of 
relativity,  it  is  never  significant  to  ask  "  What  is  Space  (or  Time)  ?  " 
For  the  symbols  "space"  and  "time"  can  never  be  put  in  any 
really  precise  proposition.1  They  are  in  fact  disappearing  symbols. 

Another  point  which  seems  worthy  of  careful  consideration  may 
be  briefly  expressed  by  saying  that  Einstein  and  some  of  his 
followers  use  the  words  that  are  used  to  denote  spatial  and  tem- 
poral relations,  in  an  ambiguous  manner.  Let  me  explain  this  by 
Einstein's  use  of  the  word  "  Simultaneous"  as  defined  by  him  in 
his  Theory  of  Relativity,  Chapter  VIII.  In  that  chapter  Einstein 
points  out  that  the  ordinary  use  of  the  word  Simultaneous  is  of  no 
use  to  Physics  except  when  used  as  connecting  two  objects  which 
can  be  observed  together.  To  overcome  this  difficulty  he  gives  a  de- 
finition of  the  way  he  proposes  to  use  the  word.  His  use  of  the 
word  may  be  provisionally  denned  like  this.  Consider  two  flashes  of 
lightning  Fx  and  F2 :  then  we  define  Fj  as  being  simultaneous  to  F2 
if  the  crests  of  the  light  waves  radiating  from  F:  and  F2  reach  some 
observer  O  situated  at  M  the  middle  point  of  the  line  Fj  F2,  simul- 
taneously. Now  if  we  carefully  consider  this  definition  we  see 
that  it  uses  the  word  "simultaneous"  in  two  quite  distinct  and 
different  ways.  Let  us  call  these  two  relations  '  primary  simultane- 
ity '  and  'secondary  simultaneity'.  The  former  represents  the 
ordinary  use  of  the  word  simultaneous,  the  latter  Einstein's  use. 
We  may  now  somewhat  emend  our  definition  and  say  Fx  and  F2 
are  secondarily  simultaneous  when  the  crests  of  the  light  waves 
radiating  from  them  reach  the  observer  O  primarily  simultaneously.2 
This  shows  that  primary  and  secondary  simultaneity  are  quite 
different  relations.  Primary  simultaneity  is  a  simple  unanalysable 
relation,  symmetrical  and  transitive.  Secondary  simultaneity  is  a 
complex  relation  analysable  in  the  way  that  Uncle  and  Grandfather 
are  analysable,  i.e.,  it  consists  in  being  related  to  a  term  or  terms 
standing  in  between  the  two  related  by  the  relation  in  question. 
In  this  case  the  relation  of  F1  to  F2  consists  in  Yl  having  the 
relation  of  '  radiating '  to  a  certain  wave  crest  of  light  say  clt  cl 
having  the  relation  of  '  primary  simultaneity '  to  another  wave 
crest  of  light  c2,  and  C2  being  '  radiated  by  '  F2.  The  importance 
of  this  distinction  between  primary  and  secondary  simultaneity 
is  simply  that,  if  the  above  is  correct,  then  it  disposes — once  and 
for  all — of  the  assertion  that  Einstein  has  proved  all  spatial 
and  temporal  relations  to  be  relative.  Primary  simultaneity 
is  not  a  relative  relation,  things  either  are  or  are  not  primarily 

1  This  is  not  a  contradiction.     In  this  sentence  the  symbol  "  space  "  is 
used  to  denote  the  symbol  "  space,"  i.e.,  the  actual  word  "  space  "  and  not 
something  beyond  the  symbol.     It  is,  of  course,  only  when  "  space  "  is 
used  in  its  usual  sense  that  it  is  a  disappearing  symbol. 

2  Further  qualifications  are  still  required  to  make  this  definition  precise, 
they  will  be  considered  further  on. 


492  K.  AINSCOUGH: 

simultaneous,  without  any  further  qualification  whatsoever.  We 
may  go  a  little  further  in  our  opposition  to  some  philosophical 
writers  on  relativity ;  but  first  let  us  make  our  definition  somewhat 
more  accurate,  although  it  will  still  be  provisional.  The  aim  and 
spirit  of  Einstein's  definitions  is  expressed  by  his  dictum,  "The 
concept  does  not  exist  for  the  physicist  until  he  has  the  possibility 
of  discovering  whether  or  not  it  is  fulfilled  in  an  actual  case  ". l 
Thus  instead  of  setting  out  on  the  perhaps  impossible  task  of 
finding  some  instrument  for  telling  whether  physical  objects  are  or 
are  not  primarily  simultaneous,  he  constructs  the  relation  secondary 
•simultaneity  of  such  a  nature  that  we  can  tell  whether  objects  are 
or  are  not  secondarily  simultaneous  with  the  senses  and  instruments 
at  our  disposal.  Now  it  will  be  admitted  that  we  do  not  observe 
light  waves  but  the  sense-data  or  sensa  caused  by  the  impinging  of 
the  light  waves  on  the  eye  and  we  may  agree  that  the  sense-data 
are  primarily  simultaneous  with  the  actual  striking  of  the  wave 
on  the  eye.  Thus,  keeping  to  Einstein's  dictum,  those  objects 
which  must  be  primarily  simultaneous  in  order  for  Fx  and  F2  to 
be  secondarily  simultaneous  will  be  objects  which  we  can  observe ; 
they  will  therefore  be  two  sense-data  of  Fx  and  F2 ;  and  our  de- 
finition will  now  read,  Fj  and  F2  are  secondarily  simultaneous 
when  the  two  sense-data  sl  and  s,,  '  of '  or  *  manifested  by '  Fj  and 
F2  respectively  and  observed  by  the  observer  O  at  the  middle 
point  M,  are  primarily  simultaneous.  Similar  definitions  may  be 
given  for  secondarily  before  and  after. 

Now  while  agreeing  with  Einstein  that  we  have  no  means  of 
telling  whether  physical  objects — as  distinct  from  sense-data — are 
primarily  before,  simultaneous  or  after  each  other,  it  by  no  means 
follows  that  they  are  not  related  by  these  relations ;  and  although 
these  relations  may  not  exist  for  the  physicist  (as  connecting 
physical  objects ;  for  they  do  exist,  even  for  the  physicist,  when 
connecting  sense-data)  they  do  exist  for  the  philosopher. 

The  theory  of  relativity  ignores  the  relations  of  primarily  before, 
simultaneous  and  after  except  when  holding  between  sense- 
data  and  by  dealing  with  the  corresponding  secondary  relations  it 
has  achieved  some  most  important  and  valuable  results,  but  this 
does  not  prove  that  the  ignored  relations  do  not  exist.  Thus 
despite  all  the  asseverations  to  the  contrary,  it  is  still  possible  to 
maintain  that  every  object  is  related  by  an  absolute  temporal 
relation  to  every  other  object,  although  in  many  cases  it  is 
impossible  to  tell  whether  an  object  is  primarily  before,  simul- 
taneous with  or  after  another  specified  object. 

It  may  be  interesting,  and  may  perhaps  further  elucidate  the 
difference  between  primary  and  secondary  simultaneity,  to  con- 
sider, from  a  logical  point  of  view,  what  is  meant  by  saying  that 
secondary  simultaneity  is  a  relative  relation,  and  how  it  happens 
that  it  is  a  relative  relation.  We  have  seen  that  when  Einstein 
says  '  Fj  is  simultaneous  to  F2 '  he  ought  to  say  *  Fj  is  secondarily 

1  Theory  of  Relativity,  p.  22. 


SOME   EEMABKS   ON   EELATIVITY.  493 

simultaneous  to  F2 ' ;  and  by  this  he  means  that  two  crests  of  light- 
waves radiated  by  Fx  and  F2  are  primarily  simultaneous,  or  more 
correctly  that  two  of  the  sense-data  Sj  and  S2  manifested  by  Fl 
and  F2  are  primarily  simultaneous ;  and  he  must  then  definitely 
specify  8j  and  S2  out  of  the  many  sense-data  manifested  by  Fl  and 
F2.  "Fj  is  secondarily  simultaneous  to  F2"  means  therefore  that 
a  certain  pair  of  the  sense-data  manifested  by  Fx  and  F2  are 
primarily  simultaneous ;  but  unless  we  specify  which  pair,  the 
assertion  remains  ambiguous  and  indeterminate,  for  there  is  a  very 
large,  if  not  an  infinite,  number  of  pairs  of  sense-data  manifested 
by  Fj  and  F2  that  are  or  could  be  observed  by  persons  situated 
around  Fa  and  F2.  Einstein  restricts  the  range  of  pairs  of  sense- 
data  by  framing  his  definition  so  that  ~Fl  is  secondarily  simultane- 
ous to  F2  when  the  pair  of  sense-data,  manifested  by  Fj  and  F2 
and  observed  by  a  person  situated  on  the  plane  passing  through 
the  middle  point  of  the  line  F:  F2  and  at  right  angles  to  it,  are 
primarily  simultaneous.  This  however  is  still  indeterminate,, 
and  the  whole  of  the  relativity  of  simultaneity  results  from  the 
indeterminateness  of  this  definition.  With  this  indeterminate 
definition  the  assertion  that  Fx  is  secondarily  simultaneous  to  F^ 
is  equivalent  to  saying  that  a  pair  of  sense-data  are  primarily 
simultaneous  ;  but  this  pair  of  sense-data  is  not  uniquely  specified, 
being  merely  specified  as  one  pair  out  of  a  class  of  pairs.  The 
assertion  '  Fx  is  secondarily  simultaneous  to  F2 '  is  really  about 
four  terms,  Fj  F2  and  two  sense-data ;  but  while  it  uniquely  specifies 
Fl  and  F2  it  does  not  uniquely  specify  the  sense-data.  Assertions 
of  this  type  may  be  called  relative,  if,  when  you  qualify  the  asser- 
tion and  in  doing  so  uniquely  specify  the  objects  otherwise  not 
uniquely  specified,  some  qualifications  make  the  complete  assertion 
true  and  some  false.  This  is  exactly  what  happens  with  '  F:  is 
secondarily  simultaneous  to  F2'.  The  qualifications  such  as  '  from 
such  a  point  of  view/  '  as  measured  from  such  a  reference  body,' 
etc.,  serve  to  specify  the  sense-data  of  Fx  and  F2  of  which  we  are 
speaking.  As  is  easily  seen,  because  of  the  constant  but  finite 
velocity  of  light,  if  some  of  these  qualifications  give  a  true  assertion 
then  some  others  will  give  a  false  assertion.  The  proposition  F1 
is  secondarily  simultaneous  to  F2  may  be  compared  with  the  pro- 
position 'P  is  highly  probable'.  Both  are  really  only  half 
propositions.  The  former  is  about  four  objects  Fx,  F2  and  two  light 
waves,  or  more  correctly,  F1?  F2  and  two  sense-data,  but  only 
specifies  half  the  objects,  i.e.,  Fx  and  F2 ;  the  latter  is  about  p 
and  a  certain  body  of  knowledge,  but  only  specifies  p. 

This  account  of  the  relativity  of  simultaneity  has  been  much  longer 
than  I  intended,  but  if  it  is  correct  it  shows,  (1)  that  there  are  two 
meanings  given  to  the  word  "  simultaneous  "  as  used  by  relativists 
and  that  only  with  one  meaning  is  simultaneity  relative.  (2)  That 
the  relativity  of  simultaneity  (a)  gives  the  same  amount  of  support 
to  the  theory  of  the  Relativity  of  truth  as  is  given  by  the  relativity 
of  propositions  like  '  P  is  highly  probable,'  which  is  no  support  at 


494  E.   AINSCOUGH  : 

all ;  (b)  has  nothing  at  all  to  do  with  the  activity  of  minds.  The 
qualifications  '  for  that  observer,'  '  as  measured  by  so  and  so/  do 
not  mean  that  the  proposition  "  Fx  is  simultaneous  to  F2 "  is  true 
for  one  person  and  false  for  another ;  as  it  stands  unqualified  it  is 
really  only  half  a  proposition  and  is  neither  true  nor  false,  the 
qualifications  are  only  ways  of  completing  it,  and  the  reference  to 
the  observer  is  merely  a  way  of  uniquely  specifying  the  two  light 
waves  or  sense-data  involved  in  Yl  being  simultaneous  to  F2 :  any 
other  way  of  uniquely  specifying  these  two  light  waves  or  sense- 
data  would  serve  equally  well. 

(3)  As  regards  subjectivity:  (a)  If  we  only  loosely  follow 
Einstein's  dictum  *  That  a  relation  is  not  to  be  used  unless  we 
have  a  possibility  of  telling  whether  it  holds  in  any  actual  case,' 
we  can  state  the  relativity  of  simultaneity  for  a  world  without 
minds  or  anything  mental  at  all ;  (b)  if  we  strictly  follow  the  above 
dictum  then  science  is  forced  to  recognise  that  we  do  not  observe 
physical  objects  but  only  the  sense-data  of  physical  objects.  This 
may  be  a  new  truth  for  science,  but  it  is  not  new  to  philosophy ; 
see  for  example  Mr.  Russell's  article  on  '  The  relation  of  sense- 
data  to  physics,'  published  in  1914. 

All  the  above  arguments  only  apply  to  simultaneity,  but  I  think 
they  can  be  generalised  to  cover  all  the  other  relations  dealt  with 
by  the  theory  of  relativity.  For  example  Dr.  Wildon  Carr  in 
MIND,  April,  1922,  p.  177,  says  "...  the  straight  line  of  every 
observer  is  curved  for  other  observers."  I  suggest  that  he  will 
find  that  such  a  proposition,  if  it  occurs  in  the  books  of  the  relativists, 
does  not  mean  that  a  line  is  both  straight  and  curved,  but  rather 
something  like  this :  "If  the  projection  of  a  moving  point  on  a 
plane  Px  is  a  straight  line,  then  its  projection  on  another  plane  P2 
where  P2  moves  relative  to  Px,  is  a  curved  line,"  or  "If  the 
appearances  (i.e.,  the  sense-data)  of  a  moving  point  from  one  body 
are  straight,  then  the  appearances  from  another  body  are  curved  ". 
And  in  general  in  all  such  propositions  there  is  a  multiplicity  of 
objects  concealed  by  the  brevity  of  expression. 

The  general  conclusion  of  these  remarks  is  that  the  theory  of 
relativity  from  the  point  of  view  of  philosophy  would  be  more 
appropriately  called  the  theory  of  half-propositions ;  that  it  has 
proved  certain  complex  relations  to  be  relative  but  that  the  relations 
usually  denoted  by  the  words  "  simultaneous,"  "  before,"  "  after," 
"  straight,"  "curved,"  etc.,  are  nob  relative;  that  we  can  only  tell 
whether  objects  have  these  non-relative  predicates  when  they  are 
objects  of  immediate  awareness,  i.e.,  sense-data ;  and  that  science 
is  beginning  to  realise  that  we  only  observe  the  sense-data  of 
physical  objects,  a  view  which  is  not  new  to  philosophy. 

The  following  flight  of  imagination  may  be  of  interest  to  philo- 
sophers and  even  to  physicists. 

"  Once  upon  a  time  there  was  an  earth  inhabited  by  a  race  of 
men,  all  totally  blind.  Their  distance  perception  depended  on 
sound.  In  the  course  of  time  there  arose  an  Einstein,  blind,  but 


SOME   EEMAEKS   ON  EELATIVITY.  495 

of  infinite  genius,  and  he  propounded  a  theory  of  relativity.  This 
theory  was  exactly  the  same  as  the  modern  theory  of  relativity 
except  that  where  we  say  'light'  they  said  'sound'.  With  this 
theory  they  proved  many  strange  results ;  for  example  nothing 
could  travel  faster  than  sound.  And  using  this  theory  two  philo- 
sophers proved  that  all  truth  was  relative.  Yet  it  was  absolutely 
true  that  mind  alone  was  real ;  there  was  no  substratum  of  any 
kind  in  nature ;  the  monads  alone  supplied  everything ;  and  step 
by  step  the  Hegelian  dialectic  carried  the  Universe  into  higher 
and  higher  degrees  of  truth  and  spiritual  reality. 

"  But  God  smiled ;  and  when  He  saw  that  man  had  become 
perfect  in  optimism  and  credulity,  He  sent  another  earth  through 
the  sky,  which  crashed  into  the  blind  men's  earth ;  and  all  again 
returned  to  nebula.1 

"  For  the  truth  of  relativity  was  itself  only  relative,  it  related  only 
to  a  small  selection  of  temporal  and  spatial  relations ;  and  there 
was  much  in  their  world  that  was  neither  man-made  nor  man- 
measured  but  moved  by  the  unmotived  forces  of  nature." 

Whether  this  is  a  true  analogue  of  the  modern  theory  of  re- 
lativity I  am  neither  sufficient  philosopher  nor  physicist  to  decide. 
But  it  would  be  well  if  it  were  so ;  for  who,  having  compared  the 
idealism  of  the  '  Reign  of  relativity '  with  the  realism  of  '  The 
Dynasts,'  will  not  agree  that  the  latter  rings  more  true  ? 

R.  AINSCOUGH. 

1  Adapted  from  the  story  told  to  Dr.  Faustus,  as  related  in  "The  Free 
Man's  Worship  ". 


VI.—  CEITICAL  NOTICES. 

Logic,  Part  II.  (Demonstrative  Inference).     By  W.  E.  JOHNSON, 
Cambridge  University  Press,  1922.     Pp.  xx,  258. 

THE  second  volume  of  Mr.  Johnson's  great  work  on  Logic  deals 
with  demonstrative  inference,  deductive  and  inductive.  It  is 
perhaps  even  more  interesting  than  the  first  volume,  on  account 
of  the  extreme  practical  importance  of  its  main  subject,  and  also 
on  account  of  the  digressions  on  such  matters  as  Magnitude  and 
Symbolism.  It  covers  the  whole  range  of  mathematical  reasoning, 
and  it  also  deals  with  those  types  of  argument  which  Mill  tried, 
not  too  successfully,  to  classify  in  his  Inductive  Methods.  In- 
cidentally it  contains  almost  the  only  good  criticism  that  has  yet 
appeared  on  a  number  of  fundamental,  but  rather  technical,  points- 
in  Russell's  Principles  of  Mathematics. 

The  work  opens  with  an  Introduction,  which  clears  up  certain 
points  in  vol.  i.,  and  restates  Mill's  criticisms  on  the  syllogism  in  • 
terms  of  the  distinction  between  Epistemic  and  Constitutive  Con- 
ditions, which  was  drawn  in  the  first  part. 

Chapter  i.  discusses  the  general  nature  of  inference,  and  its 
connexion  with  implication.  Mr.  Johnson  says  that  implication 
is  "  potential  inference,"  and  holds  that,  although  implication  and 
inference  are  distinct,  neither  of  them  can  be  understood  except  in 
terms  of  the  other.  He  thinks  that  it  follows  from  this  that  we 
ought  rather  to  say  "p  would  imply  g"  than  "p  implies  q,"  and 
he  actually  adopts  this  mode  of  statement  throughout  the  book, 
It  seems  to  me  that  this  is  not  true,  and  that  it  does  not  follow 
from  the  identification  of  implication  with  potential  inference.  If 


in  inferring  q  (if_yj™  Jmejw 

But  I  cannot  see  why  this  should  make 
us  introduce  the  potentiality  into  the  statement  about  implication, 
and  say  that  p  would  imply  q  rather  than  that  p  does  imply  q.  To 
take  an  analogy.  We  might  say  that  "threatening"  is  "potential 
injuring".  But  this  does  not  mean  that  we  ought  to  confine  our- 
selves to  statements  like  "  A  would  threaten  B  ".  On  the  contrary 
we  say  that  "  A  does  threaten  B  "  whenever  it  is  true  that  "  A 
would  injure  B  (if  he  could)  ".  This  criticism  is  not  merely  verbal, 
as  may  be  seen  from  the  following  examples.  I  should  say  :  (1) 
MaP  and  SaM  do  imply  SaP  ;  (2)  MaP  would  imply  SaP  (if  the 
premise  SaM  were  added)  ;  and  (3)  MaP  would  not  imply  SeP  under 


w.  E.  JOHNSON,  Logic.  497 

any  circumstances  (because  there  would  be  illicit  process  of  P). 
Now  I  do  not  see  how  (1)  and  (2),  which  are  clearly  different, 
could  be  distinguished  in  Mr.  Johnson's  terminology,  since  he 
would  have  to  put  (1)  in  the  form  "  MaP  and  S&M  would  imply 
S&P  ".  The  phrase  "  would  imply  "  seems  only  to  be  appropriate 
to  cases  like  (2) ;  and,  if  it  be  used  for  cases  like  (1),  we  are  left 
with  no  appropriate  expression  for  the  former. 

It  is  implied  in  ch.  i.  and  definitely  asserted  in  ch.  ii,  p.  30,  that 
"  there  is  no  single  relation  properly  called  the  relation  of  implica- 
tion ".  What  Mr.  Johnson  means  is  that  to  say  that  p  implies  q 
is  simply  to  say  that  q  could  be  inferred  from  p,  and  that  this  is 
true  when  and  only  when  one  or  other  of  several  specific  types  of 
formal  relation  hold  between  p  and  q.  In  ch.  i.,  §  4,  Mr.  Johnson 
says  that  there  are  two  fundamental  relations  between  p  and  q, 
which  justify  inference  from  the  former  to  the  latter.  These  re- 
lations are  formulated  by  him  in  two  Principles  of  Inference,  the 
Applicative  and  the  Implicative.  The  Applicative  Principle  states 
that,  if  p  be  of  the  form  All  S  is  P,  and  q  be  of  the  form  The  given 
S  is  P,  then  q  can  be  inferred  from  p.  The  Implicative  Principle 
states  that  if  p  be  a  compound  proposition  of  the  form  (x)-and- 
(x  implies  y}  whilst  q  is  of  the  form  y,  then  q  can  be  inferred  from 
p.  All  deductive  inference  rests  on  these  two  principles ;  and, 
therefore,  I  take  it,  all  implication  depends  on  one  or  other  of  the 
two  types  of  relation  mentioned  in  these  principles. 

There  is  no  particular  difficulty  about  the  Applicative  Principle, 
but  there  is  a  question  to  be  raised  about  the  Implicative  Principle. 
This  professes  to  state  one  of  the  types  of  relation  which  must  hold 
between  p  and  q  if  p  is  to  imply  q.  But  it  presupposes  that  p  itself 
already  contains  two  propositions  .r  and  y,  of  which  the  former 
implies  the  latter.  The  question  at  once  arises :  Of  what  nature 
is  the  relation  between  x  and  y,  in  virtue  of  which  x  implies  y  ? 
If  there  be  just  two  relations — the  Applicative  and  the  Implicative 
—which  give  rise  to  implication,  it  would  seem  that  the  implication 
which  is  involved  in  the  very  statement  of  the  Implicative  Principle 
must  itself  rest  on  either  the  Applicative  or  the  Implicative  rela- 
tion. If  this  be  so,  I  do  not  see  how  the  Implicative  Principle  can 
be  taken  as  expressing  one  of  the  two  fundamental  types  of  relation 
on  which  implication  depends.  It  would  seem  that  the  implication 
which  is  involved  in  the  Implicative  Principle  must  at  last  rest  on 
the  Applicative  Eelation,  on  pain  of  an  infinite  regress.  If  so,  the 
Applicative  Principle  is  more  fundamental  than  the  Implicative 
Principle. 

In  ch.  ii.,  §  3,  p.  30,  Mr.  Johnson  attempts  a  more  accurate 
statement  of  the  Implicative  Principle,  but  it  does  not  meet  the 
difficulty  that  I  have  just  pointed  out.  He  there  reformulates  the 
principle  as  follows  :  "  There  are  certain  specifiable  relations  such 
that,  when  one  or  other  of  these  subsists  between  two  propositions, 
we  may  validly  infer  the  one  from  the  other  ".  It  is,  I  think, 
perfectly  clear  that  this  is  not  a  reformulation  of  the  Implicative 

32 


498  CRITICAL  NOTICES: 

Principle,  as  originally  stated  on  p.  11,  and  that  it  is  not  consistent 
with  the  statement  on  p.  10,  that  the  Implicative  Principle  ex- 
presses one  of  the  "  two  fundamental  relations  which  will  render 
the  inference  from  p  to  q  .  .  .  formally  valid."  To  say  that  there 
are  some  relations  which  will  render  the  inference  valid  is  not  to  state 
one  of  the  two  fundamental  relations  which  justify  inference.  In 
fact  it  is  obvious  that  the  Implicative  Principle  in  its  second  formu- 
lation would  be  true  if  implication  rested  on  no  other  relation 
beside  that  mentioned  by  the  Applicative  Principle. 

There  is  thus  certainly  some  inconsistency  in  Mr.  Johnson's 
language,  and  I  am  a  good  deal  puzzled  both  as  to  what  he  really 
means  and  as  to  what  is  the  truth  of  the  matter.  I  would  tenta- 
tively offer  the  following  suggestions.  (1)  The  Applicative  Prin- 
ciple really  does  state  one  fundamental  type  of  relation  between 
two  propositions,  such  that,  whenever  it  holds,  the  former  implies 
the  latter.  (2)  If  you  grant  the  Applicative  Principle,  the  ImplT- 
cative  Principle,  in  Mr.  Johnson's  second  formulation,  immediately 
follows.  This  is  sufficient  to  show  that  the  second  formulation  does 
not  adequately  express  what  Mr.  Johnson  means  by  the  Implicative 
Principle ;  for  he  certainly  understands  by  it  something  which  is 
parallel  to  and  independent  of  the  Applicative  Principle.  (3)  The 
Implicative  Principle,  as  originally  formulated,  does  express  one 
of  the  relations  on  which  implication  rests.  But  it  only  applies 
to  the  special  case  where  one  of  the  propositions  is  a  complex,  one 
of  whose  parts  itself  involves  an  implication.  And  this  implication 
must  in  the  end  presumably  rest  on  some  other  type  of  formal  re- 
lation than  that  which  is  formulated  in  the  Implicative  Principle. 
If  it  were  true  that  there  are  only  two  fundamental  types  of  re- 
lation which  generate  implications,  it  would  seem  that  the 
Applicative  relation  must  be  more  fundamental  than  the  Implica- 
tive, in  the  sense  that  the  implication  which  is  involved  in  the 
premise  to  which  the  Implicative  Principle  is  applicable  must 
ultimately  rest  on  the  Applicative  relation.  But  I  do  not  know 
why  there  should  not  be  many  different  formal  relations  which 
give  rise  to  implications.  And,  although  Mr.  Johnson  seems  to 
hold  on  p.  10  that  there  are  only  two,  he  seems  to  make  no  such 
restriction  on  p.  30.  (4)  In  fact  I  take  it  that  there  are  many 
independent  formal  relations  which  generate  implications.  E.g., 
if  p  has  the  form  P,  and  q  has  the  form  (P  or  Q)  they  are  so  related 
that  p  implies  q.  And  this  depends  neither  on  the  Applicative  nor 
on  the  Implicative  Principle.  What  then  is  the  special  importance 
of  the  Applicative  and  Implicative  Principles  ?  (5)  It  seems  to 
me  that  their  great  importance  is  as  generative  principles.  It  is 
by  them,  and  by  them  alone,  that  we  can  deduce  chains  of  new 
truths  from  a  few  suitable  primitive  propositions.  The  primitive 
propositions  state  certain  independent  and  immediately  obvious 
formal  implications,  like  p  implies  (p  or  q).  These  give  us  premises 
of  the  kind  to  which  the  Implicative  Principle  can  be  applied. 
Again  the  Applicative  Principle  allows  us  to  substitute  what  Mr. 


w.  E.  JOHNSON,  Logic.  499 

Johnson  calls  "  connected  complexes  "  for  the  simple  terms  in  the 
primitive  propositions,  and  thus  to  reach  new  truths  by  what  he 
calls  "  functional  deduction  ".  If  we  read  a  work  like  Principia 
Mathematica,  we  see  that,  once  the  primitive  propositions  have 
been  laid  down,  all  further  progress  is  made  by  repeated  use  of 
these  two  principles.  Mr.  Johnson  is  therefore  justified  in  the 
importance  which  he  ascribes  to  them,  though,  as  I  have  said, 
some  of  the  statements  which  he  makes  about  them  seem  to  me 
puzzling,  and  at  least  verbally  inconsistent. 

Mr.  Johnson  next  makes  some  very  interesting  observations  on 
the  applicational  and  the  implicational  forms  of  inference.  As  an 
example  of  a  purely  applicational  argument  he  takes  such  an  ex-  \ 
ample  as :  "  All  propositions  have  predicates,  therefore  Matter 
exists  has  a  predicate".  Now  the  question  arises:  Is  there  not  a 
suppressed  premise,  viz.,  "  Matter  exists  is  a  proposition  "  ;  and  is 
not  the  argument  therefore  a  syllogism,  which  Mr.  Johnson  regards 
as  involving  both  the  applicative  and  the  implicative  principles  ? 
To  this  he  answers  that  the  supposed  premise  is  really,  from  the 
very  nature  of  the  case,  superfluous.  We  cannot  attach  any 
meaning  to  the  phrase  Matter  exists  unless  we  know  that  it  is  a 
proposition,  and  it  is  therefore  superfluous  to  state  that  it  is  a  pro- 
position. Mr.  Johnson  makes  two  statements  about  such  pro- 
positions which  are  verbally  inconsistent.  On  p.  14  he  says  that 
they  are  not  genuine  propositions.  At  the  foot  of  the  same  page 
he  says  that  they  are  propositions  of  a  peculiar  kind,  which  he 
proposes  to  call  structural.  A  structural  proposition  is  not  simply 
verbal,  for  it  is  not  about  words.  What  it  does  is  to  assert  a  general 
category  of  the  subject.  But  it  does  not  add  to  our  knowledge, 
because  the  subject  has  to  be  given  to  us  under  this  general  cate- 
gory before  we  can  specify  it  at  all  in  a  judgment.  A  category  is 
a  determinable  or  set  of  determinables,  and  all  judgment  consists 
of  specifying  the  determinate  forms  in  which  a  subject  exhibits 
those  determinables  under  which  it  must  be  given  to  us  if  we  are 
to  be  able  to  think  of  it  at  all.  When  a  superfluous  premise  is 
added  to  convert  a  purely  applicative  argument  into  a  syllogism, 
Mr.  Johnson  calls  the  premise  a  sub-minor. 

We  can  now  understand  Mr.  Johnson's  analysis  of  the  ordinary 
subsumptive  syllogism.  Take  the  syllogism:  "All  equilateral 
triangles  are  equiangular,  the  triangle  ABC  is  equilateral,  therefore 
it  is  equiangular  ".  Mr.  Johnson  would  analyse  this  somewhat  as 
follows  : — 

Everything  with  sides  and  angles  (M,  P)  is  equiangular  (p)  if 
•equilateral  (m). 

Therefore  the  triangle  ABC  is  equiangular  (p)  if  equilateral  (m). 
(Applicative  Principle.) 

The  triangle  ABC  is  equilateral  (m). 

Therefore  the  triangle  ABC  is  equiangular.  (Implicative 
Principle.) 

Here  M  and  P  are  the  determinables  under  which  the  object  in 


500  CBITICAL  NOTICES: 

question  is  given.  The  major  states  an  universal  connexion  be- 
tween one  determinate  under  M  and  one  determinate  under  P. 
No  premise  of  the  form  "  The  triangle  ABC  has  sides  and  angles  " 
is  needed,  for  such  a  proposition  is  merely  structural. 

Mr.  Johnson  points  out  that  it  is  possible  to  make  a  really  im- 
plicative  argument  look  applicative  by  introducing  a  superfluous 
major,  just  as  it  is  possible  to  make  a  really  applicative  argument 
look  implicative  by  introducing  a  superfluous  minor.  This  would 
happen  if  you  were  to  take  the  formal  Barbara  (MaP  .  SaM  implies 
SaP)  as  a  premise  in  some  particular  argument  in  Barbara.  There 
is  a  positive  inconsistency  in  doing  this,  for  the  principle  of  the 
syllogism  in  Barbara  states  that  the  premises  of  Barbara  are  by 
themselves  sufficient  to  justify  the  conclusion,  and  you  stultify  this 
if  you  introduce  the  principle  itself  as  &  further  premise. 

The  remaining  point  to  notice  in  this  chapter  is  Mr.  Johnson's 
clear  distinction  between  the  constitutive  and  the  epistemic  con- 
ditions of  valid  inference.  The  constitutive  condition  is  that  the 
premises  shall  be  true  and  shall  imply  the  conclusion.  The  epis- 
temic condition  is  that  you  shall  be  able  to  know  that  the  premises- 
are  true  and  that  they  imply  the  conclusion  without  having  to  know 
beforehand  that  the  conclusion  is  true.  It  is  clear  that  in  a  great 
many  cases,  e.g.,  where  the  major  is  proved  by  induction,  or  is- 
self-evident,  or  is  accepted  on  authority,  and  where  the  formal 
connexion  between  it  and  the  conclusion  can  be  intuited,  these 
conditions  are  fulfilled. 

We  may  take  chapters  ii.  and  viii.  together,  for  they  introduce  us 
to  the  unusually  extended  sense  in  which  Mr.  Johnson  uses  the 
term  induction.  The  Applicative  and  Implicative  Principles  as- 
sume that  we  have  already  got  a  number  of  universal  premises  to 
work  with.  How  do  we  get  these  ?  Always  by  something  of  the 
nature  of  induction,  according  to  Mr.  Johnson.  Now  this  might 
at  first  make  the  reader  think  that  Mr.  Johnson  is  an  empiricist ; 
but  this  is  far  from  being  so.  We  do  not  start  by  seeing  axioms  in 
their  generality,  we  get  to  know  them  by  reflecting  on  particular 
instances.  The  process  by  which  this  happens  is  called  Intuitive 
Induction.  Mr.  Johnson  defines  Induction  in  ch.  viii.,  as  a  process 
by  which  we  start  from  certain  instantial  premises  and  reach  a 
conclusion  which  is  a  generalisation  of  these  premises.  (It  would 
not  be  enough  to  say  that  the  conclusion  is  wider  than  the  least 
wide  of  the  premises,  for,  as  we  shall  see,  Mr.  Johnson  holds  that 
many  purely  deductive  arguments  have  this  characteristic.) 

Now  I  think  that  this  definition  of  induction  would  generally  be 
accepted.  And  it  is  certain  that  the  process  of  seeing  an  axiom  by 
reflecting  on  particular  instances  of  it  answers  to  this  definition,  if 
it  be  a  process  of  inference  at  all.  Hence  Mr.  Johnson  is  quite 
consistent  in  saying  that  all  principles  and  major  premises  are 
ultimately  reached  by  some  kind  of  induction.  And  it  does  not 
make  him  an  empiricist,  for  an  empiricist  would  hold  that  they  are 
all  reached  by  that  particular  kind  of  induction  which  Mr.  Johnson 


w.  E.  JOHNSON,  Logic.  501 

calls  Problematic.  Problematic  induction  leads  only  to  probable 
conclusions,  needs  special  axioms  or  postulates,  and  is  left  to  be 
treated  in  the  next  volume.  But  there  are  three  processes  of  in- 
ference which  answer  to  the  definition  of  induction,  lead  to  con- 
clusions which  are  as  certain  as  their  premises,  and  are  treated  in 
the  present  volume.  These  are  Intuitive,  Summary,  and  Demon- 
strative Induction  ;  and  it  is  the  first  of  these  which  establishes  the 
fundamental  principles  of  inference  themselves,  and  the  self-evident 
axioms  which  form  the  major  premises  of  pure  logic,  mathematics, 
etc. 

Mr.  Johnson  distinguishes  two  principles  of  Intuitive  Induction 
which  he  calls  the  Counter -applicative  and  the  Counter -implicative 
Principles.  The  first  may  be  stated  as  follows :  "  Sometimes  we 
can  see  that  what  is  true  of  this  instance  is  true  of  any  other  in- 
stance, and  then  we  can  be  sure  that  it  is  true  of  all  instances  ". 
The  second  can  be  stated  as  follows  :  "  Sometimes  when  we  have 
made  a  particular  inference  which  is  valid  we  can  see  that  its 
validity  is  due  to  a  certain  type  of  formal  relation  which  holds  be- 
tween premise  and  conclusion".  I  can  then  conclude  by  the 
Counter- Applicative  Principle  that  any  argument  of  this  form  will 
be  valid.  These  principles  cannot  be  formulated  so  that  we  can 
safely  use  them  blindly,  as  we  often  can  the  direct  Applicative  and 
Implicative  Principles.  Insight  into  the  special  subject  matter 
which  forms  our  instances  is  necessary. 

In  ch.  ii.  we  are  given  a  very  useful  division  of  propositions  into 
a  hierarchy,  which  I  will  now  exemplify.  We  have  (1)  Supreme 
principles  of  inference,  such  as  the  Applicative,  Counter-applicative, 
etc.  (2)  (a)  Formal  axioms,  such  as  p  implies  q-or-p.  (b)  Formal 
propositions  deduced  from  these  axioms  by  the  deductive  prin- 
ciples in  (1),  e.g.,  if  q  implies  r  then  p-implies-q  implies  p-implies- 
r.  (3)  (a)  Particular  instances  of  (2a),  from  which  (2a)  are  derived 
by  principles  of  intuitive  induction  contained  in  (1),  e.g.,  Jones  is  a 
knave  implies  (Broivn  is  a  fool)-or-(Jones  is  a  knave).  (3)  (b)  Par- 
ticular instances  of  (25),  e.g.,  the  particular  syllogism  in  Barbara  to 
prove  that  George  V  is  mortal.  (36)-propositions  follow  from  the 
corresponding  (3a)-propositions  by  the  Applicative  Principle.  The 
dividing  line  between  (2a)  and  (26)  is  not  of  course  perfectly  sharp, 
since  different  propositions  are  taken  as  axioms  in  different 
systems.  (4)  (a)  Experientially  certified  propositions,  like  This 
patch  is  red.  (4)  (b)  Deductions  from  these  made  in  accordance 
with  the  axioms  and  principles  of  the  higher  levels.  The  dis- 
tinction between  the  two  sub-groups  here  is  again  not  sharp,  be- 
cause no  two  people  are  agreed  as  to  precisely  what  is  certified  by 
mere  sense-experience  and  what  is  inferred  from  it. 

Chapter  iii.  deals  with  Symbolism  and  Functions,  and  is  far  the 
best  account  that  I  know  of  these  subjects.  It  contains  a  severe 
criticism  on  the  inconsistencies  of  Mr.  Russell's  account  of  pro- 
positional  functions.  Mr.  Johnson  begins  by  dividing  symbols  into 
shorthand  and  illustrative.  The  former  are  simply  abbreviations 


502  CKITICAL   NOTICES  I 

for  words  like  and,  or,  implies,  etc.  They  stand  for  formal  or 
logical  entities  and  may  be  called  formal  constants.  This  means 
that  they  have  precisely  the  same  significance  wherever  they  occur, 
and  that  this  significance  is  part  of  the  subject  matter  of  pure 
logic.  The  word  white,  or  any  shorthand  symbol  that  we  might 
use  for  it,  is  a  material  constant.  That  is,  it  is  the  name  of  a 
certain  definite  entity  which  does  not  belong  to  the  subject  matter 
of  pure  logic.  Certain  shorthand  symbols  might,  for  all  we  know 
at  the  outset,  be  either  material  or  formal.  The  figure  2  would  be 
an  example.  We  might  reasonably  think  that  it  was  a  material 
constant,  like  white,  but  it  turns  out  to  be  formal  if  we  accept 
Kussell's  and  Whitehead's  proof  that  arithmetic  contains  no 
fundamental  concepts  which  do  not  belong  to  pure  logic. 

Illustrative  symbols  are  the  P's  and  Q's,  x's  and  y's,  of  formal 
logic  and  algebra.  Mr.  Johnson  calls  such  symbols  variables. 
It  will  be  noticed  that  he  confines  the  names  constant  and  variable 
to  words  and  symbols,  and  does  not  apply  them  to  what  these 
denote.  According  to  him,  illustrative  symbols  are  singular  names 
of  a  peculiar  kind.  Their  peculiarity  is  that  they  "  stand  for  "  any 
one  of  a  whole  set  of  ordinary  singular  names.  Thus  in  "  x  is 
mortal "  the  symbol  x  stands  indifferently  for  the  names  "  Socrates," 
"  Plato,"  "  The  Man  in  the  Iron  Mask,"  and  all  other  names  (say) 
of  persons.  There  seems  to  me  to  be  a  verbal  inconsistency  in 
Mr.  Johnson's  statements  on  this  point.  After  saying  that  s  in 
"  s  is  p  "  stands  for  any  substantive- name,  he  goes  on  to  say  (p.  60) 
that  "  p  stands  for  any  one  indifferently  assignable  adjective  com- 
prised (say)  in  the  class  colour".  It  is  clear  that  he  here  means 
adjective  and  not  adjective-name;  for  the  adjective-name  "red"  is 
not  comprised  in  the  class  colour,  whilst  the  adjective  red,  which 
it  denotes,  is.  Now  it  is  clearly  inconsistent  to  make  the  variable 
s  stand  for  substantive-wawes  and  not  substantives,  whilst  you 
make  the  variable  p  stand  for  adjectives  and  not  adjective-names. 
I  think  the  verbal  confusion  arises  through  the  ambiguity  of 
"  standing- for,"  which  sometimes  means  "  acting  as  representative 
for"  and  sometimes  means  "denoting".  S  stands  for  the  names 
"  Socrates,"  etc.,  in  the  sense  that  it  equally  represents  any  one  of 
them.  P  stands  for  the  colours  red,  etc.,  in  so  far  as  it  represents 
equally  any  one  of  a  set  of  names  each  of  which  denotes  a  certain 
colour. 

Variables  are  closely  connected  with  functions,  and  functions 
according  to  Mr.  Johnson  are  bound  up  with  constructs.  A 
function  is  the  identity  of  form  which  can  pervade  many  constructs 
constructed  out  of  different  terms.  Thus  p-or-q  and  r-or-s  are 
two  constructs  out  of  r  and  s,  p  and  q,  respectively.  And  both 
exemplify  the  alternative  function.  The  terms  in  a  construct,  for 
which  substitutions  may  be  made  without  changing  the  nature  of 
the  construct,  are  called  variants  by  Mr.  Johnson  ;  and  the  illustra- 
tive symbols  for  variants  are  of  course  variables. 

This  definition  of  function  is  consistent  with  the  sense  in  which 


w.  E.  JOHNSON,  Logic.  503 

it  is  used  in  mathematics.  Mr.  Johnson  has  no  difficulty  in 
showing  that  Eussell's  various  uses  of  the  term  prepositional 
function  are  consistent  neither  with  each  other  nor  with  the 
common  usage.  The  whole  of  what  Mr.  Johnson  says  on  this 
subject  is  well  worth  reading,  and  seems  to  me  perfectly  conclusive. 

One  other  very  interesting  point  in  this  chapter  is  Mr.  Johnson's 
view  that  verbal  phrases  like  Smitk-and-Brown  or  Smith-or-Brown 
do  not  denote  genuine  logical  constructs,  whilst  phrases  like  white- 
and-hard  or  white-or-hard  do.  The  only  apparent  exception  that 
I  can  think  of  would  be  propositions  like  "Smith  and  Brown  are 
a  couple,"  which  clearly  cannot  be  analysed  into  "  Smith  is  a  couple 
and  Brown  is  a  couple  ".  But  Mr.  Johnson  would  no  doubt  meet 
this  by  his  distinction  between  the  conjunctive  and  the  enumera- 
tive  and. 

Chapter  iv.  deals  with  the  ordinary  formal  development  of  the 
syllogism.  I  need  scarcely  say  that  this  is  done  as  well  as  it  could 
be  done.  There  are  just  three  points  worth  special  mention. 
(1)  Mr.  Johnson  criticises  the  ordinary  method  of  reaching  the  valid 
moods  by  laying  down  rules  and  striking  out  the  moods  that  con- 
flict with  them.  He  justly  points  out  that  this  will  not  suffice  to 
guarantee  the  validity  of  those  that  are  left.  For  this  a  positive 
set  of  dicta  is  needed.  These  Mr.  Johnson  supplies.  (2)  In  place 
of  the  by  no  means  obvious  rule  that  a  negative  conclusion  needs  a 
negative  premise  Mr.  Johnson  substitutes  the  proposition  that 
three  classes  S,  M,  and  P,  can  be  co-extensive.  As  a  matter  of 
fact  the  rule  in  question  is  only  needed  to  cut  out  the  mood 
PaM .  MaS  implies  SoP.  To  deny  the  validity  of  this  is  equivalent 
to  saying  that  SaP,  MaS,  and  PaM  are  consistent ;  and  this  is 
equivalent  to  Mr.  Johnson's  rule,  as  the  reader  can  easily  see  for 
himself.  (4)  Mr.  Johnson  makes  a  practical  remark  which  all  who 
have  to  teach  elementary  logic  will  do  well  to  bear  in  mind.  In 
giving  examples  of  syllogisms  we  should  take  care  that  our  premises 
and  our  conclusions  are  neither  obviously  true  nor  obviously  absurd. 
The  former  error  will  make  our  students  confuse  formal  validity 
with  material  truth,  the  latter  will  make  them  think  that  the 
syllogism  is  a  mere  game.  Mr.  Johnson  recommends  examples 
from  casuistry,  economics,  and  politics,  and  supplies  some  amusing 
examples  about  the  veracity  of  my  Lord  Grey,  which  he  apparently 
regards  as  neither  axiomatic  nor  obviously  incredible. 

Chapter  v.  deals  with  what  he  calls  the  Functional  Extension  of 
the  Syllogism.  Here  the  major  is  a  numerical  law  of  the  form 
P  ==  /(M),  e.g.,  the  gas  law.  The  minor  is  of  the  form  :  "  In  this 
case  M  has  the  value  m  ".  The  conclusion  is  :  "  In  this  case  P 
has  the  value  p,  which  =  f(m)  ".  (Where  Mr.  Johnson  got  his  ex- 
traordinary expression  for  the  gas  law — T  =  239PV — is  more  than 
I  can  imagine.) 

The  rest  of  the  chapter  is  mainly  taken  up  with  cases  where  we 
are  given  (say)  P  as  a  function  of  A,  B,  C,  D,  and  we  try  to  get  (say) 
A  as  a  function  of  P,  B,  C,  D. 


504  CBITICAL  NOTICES: 

Chapter  vi.  is  extremely  important ;  for  it  deals,  under  the 
heading  of  Functional  Deduction,  with  all  the  reasoning  of  pure 
mathematics,  except  that  of  Euclidean  geometry,  which  Mr. 
Johnson  considers  to  have  certain  peculiarities  of  its  own.  The 
premises  of  functional  deductions  are  equations  of  the  form 
/(A,B,C)  =  <£(A,B,C)  for  all  values  of  the  variables.  The  argument 
is  applicative,  and  takes  place  by  substituting  connected  complexes 
for  simple  variants  in  these  functions.  If  for  A  you  substitute 
(x  +  y)  and  for  B  (x  -  y)t  for  instance,  the  two  expressions  would 
be  connected  constructs  because  of  the  common  terms  x  and  y  in 
both.  To  take  a  very  simple  example  ;  from  the  formula  (a  +  b) 
(a-  b)  =  a2  -  b2  we  derive  the  formula  ±xy  =  (x  +  y)*  -  (x  -  y)'2 
by  substituting  for  a  and  b  respectively  the  connected  complexes 
(x  +  y)  and  (x  —  y). 

Mr.  Johnson  points  out  two  important  characteristics  of  this  type 
of  reasoning.  (1)  It  is  demonstrative,  and  yet  can  lead  to  con- 
clusions which  apply  more  widely  than  the  premises,  and  (2)  it  is 
impossible  to  reduce  it  to  syllogistic  reasoning.  As  regards  the 
first  point  his  meaning  is  the  following.  Suppose  you  start  with  a 
premise  that  involves  two  distinct  variants,  A  and  B.  Then,  if  A 
be  susceptible  of  n  values  and  B  of  m,  it  is  clear  that  the  formula 
covers  mn  cases.  Now  substitute  for  A  and  B  respectively  the  two 
connected  complexes /^(A^O)  and  /2(A,B,C),  and  suppose  that  C 
is  susceptible  of  p  values.  We  shall  derive  a  general  formula  about 
A,  B,  and  C  which  will  cover  mnp  cases.  If  we  are  dealing  with 
ordinary  algebraical  formulae  all  our  variables  are  supposed  to  be 
capable  of  representing  any  number,  and  so  m  —  n  =  p  =  2  X°, 
the  number  of  the  arithmetical  continuum.  In  this  case  the  actual 
number  of  cases  to  which  the  conclusion  applies  is  the  same  as  the 
number  to  which  the  premise  applies ;  for  mnp  =  mn  =  m,  when 
we  are  dealing  with  transfinite  cardinals.  Nevertheless, \it  remains 
true  that  the  cases  covered  by  the  conclusion  contain  all  and  more 
than  all  the  cases  covered  by  the  premise ;  just  as  Space  contains 
all  and  more  than  all  the  points  on  any  straight  line,  although  the 
cardinal  number  of  points  in  a  line  is  the  same  as  that  of  the  points 
in  the  whole  of  Space. 

There  is  a  point  here  which  Mr.  Johnson  does  not  bring  out  ex- 
plicitly. Suppose  that  your  premise  was  a  formula  whose  variants 
were  definitely  confined  within  a  certain  range  of  values,  could  you 
be  sure  that  all  substitutions  of  connected  complexes  would  be 
valid  ?  It  seems  to  me  that  you  could  not.  Suppose,  e.g.,  that 
your  premise  was  a  formula  about  X  and  Y,  and  that  the  values  of 
X  were  restricted  to  integers  between  0  and  3,  and  the  values  of  Y 
were  restricted  to  integers  between  2  and  5.  Then  any  attempted 
argument  which  proposed  to  substitute  (X  +  Y)  for  X  would  break 
down.  For  the  only  possible  values  of  (X  +  Y)  would  be  4,  5,  and 
6,  all  of  which  lie  outside  the  range  of  possible  values  for  X.  Thus 
the  fact  that  the  range  of  variation  of  all  the  variables  in  an  alge- 
braical formula  is  the  whole  number-continuum  seems  to  be  an 


w.  E.  JOHNSON,  Logic.  505 

important  condition  of  the  general  validity  of  this  type  of  deduction. 

The  second  peculiarity  of  functional  deduction  may  be  illustrated 
as  follows.  By  purely  syllogistic  reasoning  we  could  not  prove 
anything  about  the  numbers  which  are  divisible  by  both  2  and  3, 
which  is  not  also  true  of  all  numbers  divisible  by  2  and  of  all 
numbers  divisible  by  3.  But  by  functional  deduction  we  can  prove 
properties  which  are  true  of  this  particular  species  of  numbers  and 
are  not  true  of  either  of  the  genera  to  which  it  belongs. 

The  last  point  to  notice  in  this  chapter  is  the  very  severe  criti- 
cism of  Eussell's  Principle  of  Abstraction.  Mr.  Johnson  agrees 
that  Mr.  Eussell  proves  the  proposition  which  goes  under  this 
name,  provided  we  grant  the  reality  of  classes,  which  Eussell 
himself  afterwards  attempts  to  deny.  But  he  holds  that  the  pro- 
position which  is  proved  is  so  tame  as  to  be  of  no  philosophical 
interest  whatever.  Mr.  Johnson  is  no  doubt  right  on  both  counts. 
But,  as  regards  the  first,  I  should  think  it  would  be  quite  easy  for 
Eussell  to  restate  the  Principle  in  terms  of  his  "  no-class  "  theory, 
for  he  does  not  get  rid  of  classes  and  substitute  nothing  whatever 
for  them.  As  regards  the  second,  the  criticism  is  perfectly  valid 
against  some  applications  which  Eussell  made  of  the  Principle 
in  his  hot  youth.  (I  think  I  am  doing  him  no  injustice  when  I 
say  that  at  one  time  he  thought  he  had  proved  the  absolute  theory 
of  time  by  the  Principle  of  Abstraction.)  But  I  presume  that  these 
were  peches  de  jeunesse,  over  which  Mr.  Eussell  would  wish  now  to 
draw  a  veil. 

Chapter  vii.  is  a  long  and  interesting  one  on  the  Different  Kinds 
of  Magnitude.  I  can  only  briefly  indicate  some  of  the  more  in- 
teresting points  in  it.  The  best  previous  treatment  of  the  subject 
is  of  course  in  the  Principles  of  Mathematics.  (Mr.  Johnson  does 
not  seem  to  be  acquainted  with  the  very  difficult  later  theory  of  the 
Principia,  which,  so  far  as  I  know,  no  philosopher  has  yet  dared 
to  criticise  or  even  mention.)  Mr.  Johnson  differs  a  good  deal  from 
Mr.  Eussell.  (1)  He  counts  numbers  as  magnitudes.  (2)  He  dis- 
tinguishes them  as  abstract  from  Concrete  Magnitudes,  like  lengths 
and  temperatures.  (3)  He  calls  the  latter  quantities,  whereas 
Eussell  confines  this  name  to  substances  having  magnitude,  such 
as  foot-rules.  (4)  He  distinguishes  between  extensional  wholes 
(classes),  whose  magnitudes  are  numbers,  and  extensive  wholes,  like 
areas  and  stretches  of  time.  He  brings  out  in  a  most  admirable 
way  the  points  of  analogy  and  difference  between  the  two.  (5)  He 
distinguishes  between  distensive  and  intensive  magnitudes.  The 
former  seem  to  be  degrees  of  difference,  and  their  zero  is  identity. 
The  zero  of  intensive  magnitude  is  non-existence.  (6)  He  holds  a 
characteristic,  and  to  my  mind  very  doubtful,  view  that  magnitudes 
of  different  kinds  can  be  multiplied  and  divided  by  each  other  to 
give  new  kinds  of  magnitude,  such  as  area  and  velocity.  The  more 
usual  view  of  course  is  that  it  is  only  the  numerical  measures  of  the 
magnitudes  that  can  be  multiplied  and  divided.  It  seems  to  me 
that  the  following  is  an  objection  to  Mr.  Johnson's  view.  He 


506  CRITICAL  NOTICES: 

admits  that  only  homogeneous  magnitudes  can  be  added.  But  multi- 
plication is  primarily  repeated  addition.  It  is  therefore  difficult  to 
see  that  he  can  consistently  hold  that  non-homogeneous  magni- 
tudes can  literally  be  multiplied  when  they  cannot  literally  be  added. 

The  chapter  contains  a  short,  but  most  illuminating,  discussion 
on  the  absolute  and  relative  views  of  Space  and  Time.  Mr.  John- 
son holds  that  two  different  controversies  have  been  confused  under 
this  head.  One  is  the  question  whether  there  are  substantival 
entities  of  a  peculiar  kind  (points  and  instants)  between  which 
spatial  and  temporal  relations  ultimately  hold,  or  whether  such  re- 
lations hold  directly  between  what  would  commonly  be  said  to 
"occupy  "  points  and  instants.  This  might  be  called  the  Substantival 
v.  the  Adjectival  Theory  of  Space  and  Time.  Mr.  Johnson  inclines 
to  the  adjectival  view,  and  dismisses  points  and  instants  as  "  sub- 
stantival myths  ".  The  other  question  is  whether  position  in  space 
or  time  can  only  be  denned  in  terms  of  relations.  This  is  a  question 
that  could  arise  just  as  much  on  the  substantival  as  on  the  ad- 
jectival view.  I  gather  that  Mr.  Johnson  inclines  to  the  non- 
relational form  of  the  adjectival  theory.  There  is  a  third  view, 
viz.,  that  points  and  instants  are  certain  classes  of  events  or 
objects.  This  has  of  course  been  greatly  developed  in  recent  times 
by  Whitehead.  I  suppose  we  might  say  that  this  makes  points  and 
instants  "  adjectival  "  as  well  as  "  substantival  myths  ".  This  view 
Mr.  Johnson  rejects  with  scorn,  but  I  am  not  altogether  persuaded 
by  his  arguments  against  it. 

The  rest  of  the  book  deals  with  all  forms  of  Induction  except  the 
problematic  kind.  We  have  already  seen  the  wide  sense  in  which 
Mr.  Johnson  uses  the  term  Induction,  and  have  described  Intuitive 
Induction.  Chapter  ix.  treats  of  what  he  calls  Summary  Induc- 
tion. This  starts  with  the  familiar  "  Perfect  Induction,"  which, 
Mr.  Johnson  points  out,  can  be  reduced  to  syllogism.  The  re- 
mainder of  the  chapter  deals  with  the  establishment  of  Euclidean 
propositions  by  the  use  of  figures.  Purely  analytical  geometry 
proceeds  wholly  by  functional  deduction,  but  its  axioms  and  there- 
fore its  conclusions  are  wholly  hypothetical.  In  Euclidean 
geometry,  according  to  Mr.  Johnson,  the  axioms  and  propositions 
are  asserted  to  be  true  of  things  in  nature.  We  might  have 
established  enough  axioms  by  summary  induction  from  figures,  and 
then  have  used  nothing  but  functional  deduction  in  our  proofs. 
But  this  has  not  in  fact  been  done  ;  the  explicit  axioms  of  Euclid 
are  not  adequate  to  guarantee  deductively  all  his  conclusions,  and 
that  is  why  figures  have  to  be  used  in  geometrical  proofs.  At 
certain  stages  in  the  proofs  summary  inductions  have  to  be  made, 
and  so  a  bad  figure  may  lead  to  false  conclusions.  Mr.  Johnson 
illustrates  this  last  point  very  happily  by  a  pleasing  fallacious 
proof  that  all  triangles  are  isosceles. 

It  remains  to  explain  how  Mr.  Johnson  supposes  that  summary 
induction  establishes  geometrical  propositions  from  figures.  The 
example  that  he  gives  is  the  establishment  of  the  axiom  that  two 


w.  E.  JOHNSON,  Logic.  507 

Euclidean  straight  lines  cannot  cut  in  more  than  one  point.  So  far 
as  I  can  understand,  the  process  is  supposed  to  be  as  follows :  We 
image  one  fixed  line  AB  and  another  cutting  it  at  A.  We  then  image 
this  other  line  AX  as  continuously  rotating  about  A.  We  see  that 
in  each  of  its  positions  it  does  not  cut  AB  again,  and  we  sum  this 
up  in  the  perfect  induction  that  it  never  cuts  it  again.  There  are 
three  points  to  notice  :  (a)  Mr.  Johnson  holds  that  we  succeed  in 
imaging  an  actual  infinity  of  positions.  I  should  have  thought  it 
was  just  as  impossible  to  image  this  as  to  sense  it.  (b)  He  insists 
that  the  process  must  be  done  by  imaging,  and  not  by  perception, 
because  "  It  is  only  through  imagery  that  we  can  represent  a  line 
starting  from  a  certain  point  and  extending  indefinitely  in  a  certain 
direction  "  (p.  202).  If  Mr.  Johnson  can  have  indefinitely  extended 
images  he  is  more  fortunate  than  I.  (c)  I  understand  Mr.  Johnson 
to  hold  that  the  axioms  of  Euclidean  geometry  are  supposed  to  be 
true  of  the  physical  objects  in  the  external  world.  I  should  have 
thought  it  was  extremely  rash  to  extend  the  geometrical  properties 
of  our  images  to  physical  objects. 

The  last  tvvo  chapters  are  devoted  to  what  Mr.  Johnson  calls 
Demonstrative  Induction.  His  treatment  falls  into  two  parts  ;  (1) 
certain  types  of  hypothetical  syllogism  in  which  an  instantial 
premise  leads  to  an  universal  conclusion,  and  (2)  his  substitute  for 
Mill's  Methods.  The  typical  example  of  hypothetical  argument 
which  Mr.  Johnson  gives  is  of  the  form  :  "If  some  S  is  P  then  all 
T  is  U;  but  this  S  is  P  ;  therefore  all  T  is  U  ".  It  is  thus  an 
argument  whose  major  is  a  hypothetical  proposition  with  a  par- 
ticular antecedent  and  an  universal  consequent.  The  other  premise 
is  the  assertion  of  a  certain  instance  in  accordance  with  the  ante- 
cedent. The  conclusion  is  of  course  the  assertion  of  the  universal 
consequent.  Now  no  one  would  deny  the  validity  of  such  argu- 
ments ;  the  only  question  is  whether  they  can  be  called  inductive, 
even  in  the  wide  sense  in  which  induction  is  defined  by  Mr.  Johnson. 
In  their  most  general  form  they  hardly  can  be  called  inductive,  for 
the  conclusion  is  not  a  generalisation  of  the  instantial  minor.  Mr. 
Johnson  next  quotes  examples  in  which  he  alleges  that  the  con- 
clusion really  is  a  generalisation  of  the  instantial  minor.  One 
example  is  :  "If  some  boy  in  the  school  sends  up  a  good  answer, 
then  all  the  boys  will  have  been  well  taught ;  the  boy  Smith  has 
sent  up  a  good  answer;  therefore  all  the  boys  have  been  well 
taught ".  I  cannot  myself  see  that  the  conclusion  of  this  is  a 
generalisation  of  the  instantial  minor.  I  should  have  thought  that 
it  was  obvious  that  "  All  the  boys  have  been  well  taught  "  could  only 
be  a  generalisation  of  such  an  instantial  proposition  as  "  The  boy 
Smith  has  been  well  taught"  whereas  the  actual  minor  is  "  The 
boy  Smith  has  sent  up  a  good  answer".  I  therefore  see  no  ground 
for  counting  even  this  argument  as  inductive.  In  fact  the  only 
argument  of  this  type  which  would  be  genuinely  inductive,  in  Mr. 
Johnson's  sense,  would  be  of  the  form  :  "  If  some  boys  in  the  house 
have  measles,  all  will  have  measles  ;  the  boy  Smith  has  measles  ; 


508  CEITICAL   NOTICES: 

therefore  all  the  boys  in  the  house  will  have  measles  ".  This  is 
demonstrative  and  inductive,  and  not  altogether  remote  from  the 
real  facts  of  life,  as  housemasters  know  to  their  cost. 

Mr.  Johnson  points  out  that  arguments  of  this  kind  really  are 
common  in  science.  From  what  we  know  of  the  atomic  theory  we 
can  say  with  great  probability  that  "  If  one  sample  of  Argon  has  a 
certain  atomic  weight,  then  all  samples  of  Argon  will  have  the 
same  atomic  weight".  We  then  find  that  the  atomic  weight  of  a 
certain  particular  specimen  is  40.  And  we  are  justified  in  con- 
cluding that  all  specimens  of  Argon  will  have  atomic  weight  40, 
provided  our  major  is  correct. 

I  will  end  with  an  account  of  Mr.  Johnson's  substitute  for  Mill's 
Methods.  He  sees  clearly  that  Mill  was  confused  as  to  the  nature 
of  the  methods.  Really  they  should  be  purely  demonstrative, 
leading  to  conclusions  which  are  as  certain  as  their  premises. 
•And  their  premises  have  to  be  borrowed  from  the  results  of  pro- 
blematic induction.  Now  Mill  hardly  distinguished  the  Method  of 
Agreement  from  Induction  by  Simple  Enumeration,  which  is  a 
form  of  problematic  induction.  Again,  he  thought  that  the  ultimate 
majors  of  these  arguments  were  very  wide  general  principles,  like 
the  Law  of  Causation.  Mr.  Johnson  points  out  that  they  need 
much  more  definite  and  concrete  majors  before  they  can  be  rendered 
genuinely  demonstrative.  These  majors  have  to  be  established  by 
problematic  induction,  and  they  take  the  following  form  in  the 
simplest  case.  Certain  sets  of  generic  characteristics  ("  determin- 
ables," as  Mr.  Johnson  calls  them)  determine  a  certain  other 
generic  characteristic.  Bach  determinable  is  susceptible  of  a 
number  (finite  or  transfinite)  of  specific  modifications.  E.g., 
"colour"  is  a  determinable,  and  a  certain  definite  shade  of  red  is 
a  determinate  under  it.  And  of  course  each  determinate  is  capable 
of  being  exhibited  in  an  infinite  number  of  particular  instances. 
With  these  preliminaries  we  can  state  the  kind  of  major  premise 
which  will  serve  for  a  demonstrative  induction.  We  need — if  I 
understand  Mr.  Johnson  rightly — in  the  simplest  case,  to  establish 
a  proposition  of  the  following  kind  as  a  premise.  (1)  In  all  cases 
where  all  the  determinables  ABCD  are  present  the  determinable  P 
is  present ;  and  no  other  determinable  (say  Q)  is  present  in  all 
these  cases.  (2)  In  all  cases  where  the  determinable  P  is  present 
all  the  determinables  ABCD  will  be  found ;  and  there  will  be  no 
other  determinable  (say  E)  common  to  all  these  cases.  When 
such  a  premise  has  been  established  the  demonstrative  induction 
rests  on  certain  axioms  about  adjectival  determination.  Let  us 
see  how  much  freedom  this  premise  allows  us.  If  I  interpret  Mr. 
Johnson  rightly  it  is  quite  possible  (1)  that  we  should  have  abcdp 
and  a'b'cdp,  for  instance.  (2)  It  is  even  possible  that  we  should 
have  abcdp  and  a'bcdp.  But  (3),  if  this  be  so,  we  cannot  have 
a'bcdp" ' .  In  fact  we  may  here  conclude  A.bcdp,  i.e.,  that,  although  the 
presence  of  A  in  some  form  is  necessary  to  the  production  of  p  yet 
its  variations  are  irrelevant  to  the  variations  of  p,  so  long  as  BCD 


w.  E.  JOHNSON,  Logic.  509 

have  the  specific  values  bed.  (4)  Even  if  we  have  Abcdp,  we  must 
not  conclude  that  variations  of  A  will  be  irrelevant  to  variations- 
of  p  when  BCD  are  not  confined  to  the  specific  values  bed.  We 
may  perfectly  well  have  ab'cdp'  in  spite  of  Abcdp.  (5)  Lastly,  if 
we  find  that  abcdp  and  a'bcdp',  then  we  cannot  have  a'bcdp  or 
d'bcdp' ;  we  must  have  abcdp".  I.e.,  if  any  variation  of  A  is 
relevant  to  variations  of  P,  while  BCD  have  the  specific  values  bed, 
all  variations  of  A  will  entail  variations  of  P  under  the  same  con- 
ditions. But  (6),  even  if  this  be  so,  we  must  not  conclude  that, 
when  the  specific  values  of  BCD  are  no  longer  confined  to  bed,  we 
cannot  have  such  a  case  as  a"b'cdp. 

In  all  these  arguments  it  is  assumed  that  the  determinables 
under  discussion  are  "simplex,"  i.e.,  that  A,  for  example,  is  not 
really  a  complex  of  two  or  more  determinables,  say  AjA^  It  is 
also  assumed  that  ABCD  are  all  independently  variable.  Taking, 
such  a  major  as  this,  and  supplying  it  with  different  sorts  of  minor 
from  our  observations,  it  is  clear  that  we  can  arrive  at  four  different 
types  of  conclusion,  according  to  the  nature  of  the  factual  minor 
supplied.  (1)  If  all  are  simplex,  and  abcdp  and  a'bcdp  then  Abcdp. 
(2)  If  all  are  simplex,  and  abcdp  and  a'bcdp',  then  a'bcdp",  where 
p"  differs  from  both  p  and  from  p'.  (3)  If  all  be  simplex,  and 
abcdp  and  a'bcdp'  then  a"cdp  must  be  b" ',  where  V  differs  from  b. 
(4)  If  abcdp  and  a'bcdp'  and  a'bcdp  then  A  cannot  be  simplex  but 
must  be  of  the  form  A1A2. 

These  four  types  of  argument  Mr.  Johnson  calls  respectively 
the  figures  of  Agreement,  Difference,  Composition,  and  Resolution. 
The  reasons  for  the  first  two  names  are  obvious.  In  the  third,, 
after  a  variation  in  A  has  produced  a  variation  in  P  we  find  that 
a  further  variation  in  A  does  not  produce  the  expected  further 
variation  in  P.  We  therefore  conclude  that  this  variation  in  A 
has  been  compounded  with  and  neutralised  by  a  variation  in  some 
other  factor  such  as  B.  In  the  fourth  we  have  the  same  sort  of 
facts  to  explain ;  but  we  know  that  there  has  been  no  variation  in 
the  other  factors,  whilst  we  are  not  sure  that  all  the  factors  are 
simplex.  We  are  therefore  forced  to  resolve  the  factor  about  whose 
simplicity  we  were  doubtful  into  two  or  more  factors. 

Mr.  Johnson  illustrates  his  Figures  and  then  deals  with  the  more 
complex  and  actual  case  of  a  determined  result  involving  several 
determinables  PQRS,  say.  The  general  principles  involved  are 
the  same,  and  will  be  clear  to  anyone  who  has  understood  the 
argument  in  the  simpler  cases. 

I  think  there  can  be  no  doubt  whatever  that  Mr.  Johnson's 
Figures  are  a  great  improvement  on  Mill's  Methods,  both  in  logical 
rigour  and  in  approximation  to  the  actual  procedure  of  scientists. 
There  is,  however,  one  criticism  which  strikes  me.  Surely  the 
axioms  on  which  Mr.  Johnson  bases  his  Figures  wholly  ignore  the 
possibility  of  the  laws  of  adjectival  determination  sometimes  taking 
a  periodic  form.  Suppose  it  happened  that  P  was  so  connected 
with  ABCD  that— 

P  =  A  sin  (BC  +  D). 


510  CEITICAL   NOTICES: 

Then  we  should  have  p  =  a  sin  (be  +  d)  and  p'  =  a  sin  (b'c  +  d) 
and  yet  p  =  a  sin  (b"c  +  d),  provided  that  b"  is  and  b'  is  not  equal 
to  b  +  2?rn/c.  Nor  is  this  an  outrageous  supposition,  since  electro- 
magnetism  mainly  rests  on  laws  of  this  kind. 

I  have  perhaps  said  enough  to  show  that  Mr.  Johnson's  book  is 
one  which  no  one  interested  in  Logic  and  Scientific  Method  can 
afford  to  neglect.  It  contains  many  controversial  points,  as  any 
thorough  treatment  of  such  difficult  subjects  must  do  ;  but  I  have 
no  hesitation  in  saying  that  it  is  the  best  book  that  has  appeared, 
or  is  likely  to  appear  for  a  long  time,  on  the  absolutely  fundamental 
questions  with  which  it  deals. 

C.  D.  BROAD. 


De  ^Explication  dans  les  Sciences.  Par  EMILE  MEYEESON.  Paris  : 
Payot  &  Cie,  1921.  2  vols.  Pp.  xiv,  338  and  469. 
Price  40  fr. 

I. 

M.  MEYEESON  here  deals  from  a  different  point  of  view  with  the 
problem  which  he  handled  with  so  much  distinction  in  Identite 
et  Eealite  (1st  ed.,  1908,  2nd  ed.,  much  enlarged,  1912  :  Paris, 
Felix  Alcan).  These  two  books  deserve  to  be  widely  known  in  this 
country,  both  to  philosophers  and  to  scientists.  M.  Meyerson's 
style  is  a  model  of  concreteness  and  lucidity ;  his  argument  is 
wonderfully  continuous,  in  spite  of  the  wealth  of  illustration  drawn 
from  the  history  of  science  with  which  he  enforces  it. 

The  problem  is  one  of  theory  of  knowledge  :  to  discover  "  the 
essential  principles  of  thought."  The  method  is  to  examine  the 
processes  of  scientific  reasoning  as  actually  exhibited  in  the  history 
of  science  (ix.).  His  work  is  not  metaphysics,  but,  he  hopes, 
"  prolegomena  to  any  future  metaphysics"  (xii.). 

In  this  examination  he  does  not  trust  the  scientist's  own  accounts 
of  his  processes,  but  studies  the  scientist  at  work,  so  as  to  see  how 
he  acts.  M.  Meyerson's  study  then  can  be  described  as  a  study  of 
scientific  reasoning  from  a  behaviourist  standpoint  (e.g.,  Identite 
et  Eealite,  432-433). 

In  Identite  et  Eealite  this  investigation  was  pursued  empiri- 
cally. In  the  present  book  an  attempt  is  made  to  justify  the  same 
results  by  a  more  deductive  consideration  of  the  conditions  of 
scientific  explanation  as  such. 

II. 

It  is  assumed  throughout  that  man's  reason  is  an  instrument 
which  has  to  be  applied  to  the  original  data  of  experience  (sensa- 
tions) in  order  that  a  world  may  be  experienced  at  all.  This 
instrument,  reason,  has  a  structure,  a  form,  which  has  remained 
without  evolution  at  least  during  historic  times,  although  there  has 
been  a  steady  evolution  in  the  products  of  reasoning  as  applied  to 


EMILE  MEYERSON,  De  I' Explication  dans  les  Sciences.     511 

the  systematisation  of  experience.  It  is  this  constant  form  of 
human  reason  that  M.  Meyerson  has  endeavoured  to  bring  to 
light  (ii.,  369  ff.). 

One  result  follows  at  once,  which  helps  to  make  the  author's 
historical  studies  so  valuable.  If  human  reason  in  its  essential 
form  does  not  change,  then  all  the  scientific  theories  of  the  past  are 
as  reasonable  as  those  of  the  present ;  and  if  we  can  think  away 
later  discoveries  and  new  points  of  view  and  put  ourselves  at  the 
old  point  of  view,  we  shall  see  how  reasonable  that  point  of  view 
was  ;  and  this  is  a  duty  enjoined  on  the  historian.  The  importance 
of  this  cannot  be  too  much  stressed.  M.  Meyerson 's  favourite 
example  is  the  history  of  the  phlogiston  theory ;  but  the  whole  of 
his  work  bears  the  impress  of  it  on  every  page. 


III. 

We  can  best  bring  out  the  author's  attitude  to  his  problem  by 
noting  his  account  of  (a)  atomism,  and  (b)  theories  of  conservation 
(ii.,  319  ff.). 

(a)  Atomism  was  the  first  scientific  fruit  of  the  sphere  of 
Parmemdes.  It  was  fully  matured,  so  far  as  its  form  is  concerned, 
at  its  birth ;  and  subsequent  development  has  not  altered  its  main 
lines.  It  has  been  throughout  the  ages,  and  continues  to  be  to-day, 
the  most  powerful  of  all  instruments  in  scientific  discovery.  It  is 
peculiarly  fitted  to  bring  home  to  us  the  nature  of  human  reason. 
While  the  one  unchanging  of  Parmemdes  represents  human  reason 
taking  possession  of  itself  in  its  purity  once  for  all  (with  absolute 
finality),  atomism  represents  human  reason  straight  away  adopting 
its  characteristic  attitude  to  the  world  of  existence.  Atomism 
asserts  persistence  and  admits  change.  It  makes  change  quasi- 
rational  by  reducing  it  to  variation  of  one  type,  and  that  the  most 
akin  to  reason,  viz.,  change  of  position,  or  grouping,  in  space. 
"  II  faut,"  says  Cournot  in  a  passage  which  M.  Meyerson  took  as 
one  of  the  mottoes  of  Identite  et  Bealite,  "  que  les  inventeurs  de  la 
doctrine  atomistique  soient  tombes  de  prime  abord,  ou  sur  la  clef 
meme  des  phenomenes  naturels,  ou  sur  une  conception  qui  la  con- 
stitution de  1'esprit  humain  lui  suggere  inevitablement."  In  a  way 
they  did  both  ;  but  fundamentally — and  it  is  on  this  that  we  wish  to 
concentrate  at  the  moment — the  latter. 

How  far,  then,  it  may  be  asked,  does  Atomism,  which  is  a  priori 
in  that  it  received  its  complete  outline  at  a  time  when  experimental 
evidence  for  it  was  impossible,  represent  "  une  conception  qui  la 
constitution  de  1'esprit  humain  lui  suggere  in6vitablement  ?  " 

Atomism  contains  aspects  which  do  not  satisfy  reason,  and  which 
must  therefore  be  regarded  as  foreign  to  the  nature  of  reason. 
Atoms  have  definite  shapes  and  sizes  and  positions  in  space.  Why 
just  these  ?  reason  must  ask,  but  cannot  answer.  Atoms  act  on 
one  another ;  and  reason  has  never  been  able  to  comprehend  tran- 
sitive action.  Atomism  is  rational,  we  see,  only  to  the  extent  to 


512  CRITICAL  NOTICES: 

which  it  satisfies  the  demand  of  the  mind  for  that  which  remains 
identical  without  changing  ;  its  irrationality  is  due  to  the  fact  that 
it  involves  a  diversity  which  cannot  be  rationalised. 

Here  is  one  of  M.  Meyerson's  essential  points.  The  only  genu- 
inely rational  would  be  the  purely  identical  which  contained  no  di- 
versity. But  such  a  pure  identity  could  not  exist ;  it  would  be  a 
strict  non-entity  (see  ii.,  335,  n.  5,  for  a  note  on  identity).  Thus 
reason  as  applied  to  existence  is  self-contradictory,  since  it  postu- 
lates a  diver&ity  which  it  cannot  fully  assimilate.  Hence  in  seek- 
ing to  render  existence  completely  rational,  we  are  started  on  a. 
path  which  would  end  in  the  complete  destruction  of  existence — in 
acosmisrn.  Yet,  and  this  is  the  paradox  of  the  situation,  it  is  just 
the  strenuous  endeavour  to  accomplish  this  task  which  has  pro- 
vided the  most  fruitful  results  in  the  discovery  of  the  laws  of 
nature. 

Atomism,  as  we  see,  shows  reason  coming  to  terms  with  that 
which  is  apparently  only  partially  rational.  It  takes  various  shapes 
at  various  epochs,  but  the  same  general  character  underlies  it 
always.  It  leaves  sensation  aside  as  an  irrational  which  it  make& 
no  attempt  to  subdue.  The  history  of  the  evolution  of  atomism  is 
a  history  of  attempts  to  bring  more  and  more  of  the  diversity  of 
nature  inside  the  atomic  frame,  of  partial  success  beyond  all  hopes, 
and  of  a  sudden  emergence,  from  time  to  time,  in  an  unexpected 
place,  of  a  new  brute  diversity  which  resists  reduction.  The 
Brussels  conference  of  physicists  of  1911  furnishes  M.  Meyerson 
with  many  reflections  on  this  matter  (i.,  39  ff.,  and  passim).. 
Viewed  from  another  side,  the  history  of  atomism  shows  a  series 
of  attempts  to  reduce  the  multiplicity  demanded  by  the  form  of 
atomism  itself,  to  determinations  of  pure  space :  always  with  the 
same  partial  success  and  lack  of  success. 

(b)  Theories  of  conservation.  At  various  times  various  principles- 
of  conservation  have  been  held  in  science  :  some  have  proved  er- 
roneous, and  some  have  up  to  the  present  been  confirmed.  All  have 
the  same  character.  They  are  partly  a  priori,  partly  a  posteriori* 
From  reason  comes  the  demand  for  something  which  persists  ; 
from  experience  comes  the  suggestion  for  what  it  is  that  persists. 
M.  Meyerson  is  extremely  happy  in  his  treatment  of  these  prin- 
ciples ;  particularly  in  showing  the  rationality  of  the  qualitative 
conceptions  of  the  middle  ages,  of  the  theory  of  phlogiston,  of 
caloric.  Principles  of  conservation,  he  shows,  are  plausible,  i.e. 
we  are  disposed  to  accept  them  on  insufficient  evidence  because  of 
their  promise  to  satisfy  reason.  Eeason  wants  something  to  per- 
sist, and  every  principle  of  conservation  has  been  accepted  because 
it  both  satisfied  reason  in  this  respect  and  showed  itself  capable  of 
practical  application.  He  is  extremely  happy  in  the  way  in  which 
he  shows  how,  once  such  a  principle  has  won  acceptance,  it  leads 
scientists  to  see  as  a  fact  the  entity  which  persists,  and  thus  a  bar- 
rier of  fact  is  erected  against  a  new  principle  of  conservation. 
Each  new  principle  thus  has  to  fight  strenuously  before  it  slays 


E'MILE  MEYEESON,  De  ^Explication  dans  Us  Sciences.     513 

its  rival,  but,  once  its  rival  is  slain,  it  alters  all  the  empirical  facts 
in  its  own  favour.  M.  Meyerson's  account,  again,  of  the  way  in 
which  this  principle  is  used  implicitly  in  the  building  up,  on  the 
level  of  common  sense,  of  a  world  of  independent  objects,  enables 
him  to  reach  one  of  his  central  theses,  viz.,  that  the  world  of 
common  sense  is  a  half-way  house  on  the  same  road  to  acosmism 
as  that  on  which  science  is  travelling. 

/   IV. 

The  history  of  science,  then,  reveals  a  progressive  attempt  on  the 
part  of  the  scientist  to  show  nature  rational,  and  an  ever  renewed 
failure  to  do  so.  The  existence  of  science  proves  that  nature  is 
partly  in  accord  with  reason ;  the  existence  of  the  irrationals  (the 
irreducible  characteristics  which  have  either  to  be  accepted  as  brute 
facts  in  the  science  or  set  aside  as  falling  beyond  the  power  of  the 
science  to  include  even  as  brute  facts)  which  arise  in  every  science 
indicates  that  this  accord  is  only  partial ;  the  unexpectedness  of  the 
irrationals  is  a  warning  that  we  cannot  map  out  beforehand  the 
extent  to  which  nature  is  rational. 

The  whole  history  of  science  for  M.  Meyerson  is  summed  up  at 
the  beginning  of  its  course  in  Plato's  words  (which  he  takes  as  the 
motto  of  De  V Explication)  :  "  accommodating  by  violence  the  nature 
of  the  other  to  that  of  the  same  "  (ii.,  315  n.).  The  scientist  refuses 
what  nature  offers,  and  lays  violent  hands  on  her,  forcing  her  di- 
versity into  identities  ;  and  nature  shows  herself  pliable — but  you 
never  know  when  she  will  resist. 

A  very  important  example  of  this  is  to  be  seen  in  the  concepts 
the  scientist  uses  such  as  pure  silver,  a  perfect  gas,  a  weightless 
lever,  a  body  moving  under  no  external  forces,  etc.  These  things 
none  of  them  exist ;  nor  does  nature  suggest  them  of  herself ;  but 
they  are  the  basis  of  our  whole  treatment  of  nature. 

"  Mais  alors  n'est-ce  pas  la,  de  la  part  de  la  science,"  he  asks, 
"  une  attitude  contradictoire,  n'est-il  pas  etrange  qu'elle  etudie  le 
phenomene,  qui  n'est  que  changement,  a  1'aide  d'un  principe  qui 
tend  a  affirmer  1'identite  de  I'antec6dent  et  du  consequent,  c'est- 
a-dire  a  nier  tout  changement,  et  qu'elle  se  serve,  en  general,  afin 
de  penetrer  1'essence  des  choses,  dont  elle  maintient  la  realite, 
d'une  conception  qui  aboutit  a  la  negation  de  toute  diversite? 
N'est  il  pas  paradoxal  au  plus  haut  point  qu'elle  reussisse  dans 
cette  entreprise,  que  la  nature,  dans  une  certaine  mesure,  semble 
se  montrer  p6netrable,  plastique,  a  1'egard  d'une  th6orie  qui  vise  a 
la  demontrer  non-existante  ?  "  (ii.  349). 

Nevertheless,  it  is  so. 

V. 

Two  concepts  are  needed  to  express  the  full  complex  task  of 
science ;  M.  Meyerson  calls  them  respectively  the  concept  of  law, 
and  the  concept  of  cause.  He  uses  the  word  cause  in  the  sense 

33 


514  CEITICAL   NOTICES: 

in  which  it  was  used  before  Hume  identified  it  with  invariable, 
sequence  ;  and  he  keeps  the  word  law  for  the  notion  of  invariable 
sequence,  or  orderliness.  Cause,  then,  for  him,  emphasises  the 
element  of  identity  ("  causa  aequat  effectum  :  ex  nihilo  nihil  fit ")  ; 
while  law  emphasises  the  element  of  diversity,  an  emphasis  which 
reaches  its  height  in  the  principle  of  Carnot.  Each  principle 
is  unworkable  if  separated  from  the  other ;  this  M.  Meyerson  brings 
out  both  by  the  whole  argument  of  Identite  et  Eealite.  and  by  his 
trenchant  criticism  of  positivism  in  De  I' Explication.  Yet  he  is  not 
satisfied  that  it  is  possible  to  reduce  either  principle  to  the  other. 
However  intimately  bound  up  together,  the  two  principles,  he 
insists,  are  really  antagonistic.  Causality  in  its  ideal  form  (of 
absolute  identity)  is  an  ideal  infinitely  remote,  and  suicidal ;  while 
we  hopefully  assert  the  complete  orderliness  of  nature  here  and 
now  (with  the  exception  of  a  large  field  which  he  leaves  open  for 
volition)  (ii.,  336-337  :  cf.  Identite  et  Eealite,  428). 

VI. 

The  direct  logical  approach  to  this  position  is  made  in  the 
chapters  of  Book  II.,  notably  in  chapters  iii.  and  v.,  which  deal 
with  deduction.  Book  III.,  which  discusses  the  nature  philosophies 
of  Schelling  and  Hegel  (L' Explication  Globale),  forms  an  important 
indirect  logical  approach. 

The  nature  philosophies  of  Schelling  and  Hegel,  M.  Meyerson 
thinks,  are  capable,  in  their  contrast,  of  throwing  clear  light  on 
the  genuine  nature  of  scientific  explanation ;  and  he  endeavours  to 
put  them  to  this  useful  purpose.  Hegel's  description  of  the  method 
of  abstract  science,  he  considers,  is  "  just  and  profound  "  ;  it  has 
been  neglected  by  scientists  because  Hegel's  object  in  describing 
science  was  to  show  how  defective  science  is.  Hegel,  and  M. 
Meyerson  agrees,  insists  that  explanation  in  the  physical  sciences 
rests  on  the  concept  of  persistence,  or  the  identical.  The  whole 
work  of  science  appeared  to  him  to  reduce  to  an  immense  tautology, 
for  he  did  not  see  the  extent  to  which  the  concept  of  spatial  ar- 
rangement of  identical  elements  could  be  used  in  scientific  explana- 
tion. In  pure  mathematics,  M.  Meyerson  thinks,  Hegel  was 
willing  to  admit  the  value  of  the  tautology;  but  just  because 
mathematics  proceeds  by  a  setting  aside  of  diversity,  Hegel  regarded 
it  as  incapable  of  serving  as  a  type  of  genuine  knowledge. 

The  precise  sense  in  which  mathematics  treats  entities  as 
identical  which  it  knows  not  to  be  so,  setting  aside  temporarily  all 
diversity  which  stands  in  the  way  of  their  complete  identification, 
M.  Meyerson  treats  in  chapter  v.  His  account  is  based  on  the  fact 
that  what  exists  shows  itself  individual  and  in  every  detail  singular. 
Two  things  can  be  similar  in  a  certain  respect  but  not  identical ; 
if  the  universals  which  form  the  staple  of  reasoning  are  to  arise, 
reason  must  force  similars  into  an  identity  which  they  really  do 
not  show.  It  is  clear  that  M.  Meyerson  is  concerned  only  to  pre- 


EMILE  MEYEESON,  De  I' Explication  dans  les  Sciences.     515 

else  a  situation  and  not  to  propound  a  final  theory  of  the  relation 
of  universal  to  particular ;  but  at  the  same  time  he  does  definitely 
speak  as  if  there  could  be,  in  his  opinion,  no  ultimate  way  of 
harmonising  similars  and  identities.  Yet  (as  we  have  seen)  it  is 
one  of  his  final  conclusions  that  nature  is  partly  rational,  and  by 
this  he  certainly  does  not  mean  that  some  parts  of  nature  are 
wholly  rational.  What  ultimate  meaning,  then,  can  be  given  to 
the  phrase  "  partly  rational,"  if  the  rational  is  the  pure  identical 
and  all  diversity  is  irrational  ? 

We  can  say,  I  think,  that  M.  Meyerson's  account  of  reason  in- 
volves that  in  principle,  nature  is  in  every  part  completely  irrational. 
For  the  only  truly  rational  would  be  a  pure  identity  which  was 
not  given  to  reason,  but  was  provided  by  reason  out  of  itself.  The 
first  approximation  to  the  truly  rational  is  a  number  of  entities, 
such  as  the  Ax  and  A2  which  form  the  real  basis  of  the  principle  of 
identity  "  A  is  A  "  :  where  what  we  do  is  to  affirm  that  "  Ax  is  A2," 
neglecting  as  irrelevant  the  difference  indicated  by  the  suffixes. 
We  have  here  an  instance  of  what  M.  Meyerson  would  call 
"partial"  rationality;  but  it  is  clear  that  on  his  view  of  identity 
such  partial  rationality  is,  strictly  speaking,  completely  irrational. 
We  have  identification  but  not  identity  in  the  proposition  Ax  is  A2. 

The  identification  may  rest,  in  this  case,  on  the  basis  of  an  ob- 
vious similarity  (or  an  inability  on  our  part  to  distinguish  precise 
differences),  as  when  we  identify  two  animals  as  sheep :  it  is  then 
spontaneous.  It  may  however  involve  force,  and  have  to  be  sought 
for :  as  where  steam  and  ice  are  declared  to  be  identical  in  sub- 
stance. What  we  see  presents  difference  and  not  sameness  :  what 
we  require  if  we  are  to  comprehend  is  identity :  we  compromise 
with  "  identification  ".  But  in  principle,  as  I  have  said,  this  iden- 
tification is  absolutely  irrational.  Nature  can  however  be  described 
as  "  partly  rational "  in  the  sense  that  it  is  amenable,  within  limits, 
to  treatment  by  this  process  of  identification  (see  ii.,  139  ff.) 

VII. 

I  think  M.  Meyerson  has  fully  made  out  his  case  that  the  suc- 
cesses of  science  have  been  won  by  a  constant  endeavour  to  force 
nature  into  certain  moulds.  I  think  he  has  shown  that  reason 
must  play  an  active  forceful  role,  making  demands  which  continu- 
ally go  beyond  anything  nature  suggests  and  beyond  anything 
which  nature  ever  fully  satisfies.  But  I  think  his  identification  of 
the  purely  rational  with  the  purely  identical  is  too  forceful.  To 
take  one  instance.  The  two  sides  of  the  formula  "  existentia  est 
singularium  ;  scientia  est  de  universalibus  "  (i.,  14-15),  do  not  come, 
one  from  sense,  the  other  from  reason.  It  is  not  enough  to  say  (as 
he  does,  quoting  from  M.  Eoustan's  excellent  Psychologie)  that 
"  tout  ce  qui  est  pergu  par  nos  sens  se  morcelle  en  sensations  par- 
ticulieres,"  while  "  tout  ce  qui  est  congu  par  notre  entendement 
prend  la  forme  d'id^e  generale"  (i.,  15).  The  conflict  between 


516  CBITICAL  NOTICES: 

"  singularia  "  and  "  universalia  "  is  not  one  between  reality  and 
science,  sensation  and  understanding.  It  is  one  within  reason  it- 
self. Both  sides  of  the  formula  come  equally  from  reason  :  and 
both  sides  come  only  from  reason  in  contact  with  the  material  of 
perception.  To  describe  science  as  pursuing  identity  in  what  is 
merely  presented  as  diverse  is  to  describe  it  only  from  one  side  : 
science  equally  pursues  the  completely  definite,  the  singular,  in  what 
is  merely  presented  as  diverse.  It  is  reason  that  insists  that  atoms, 
if  they  exist,  must  have  a  definite  shape ;  just  as  much  as  it  is 
reason  that  insists  that  there  must  be  a  reason  why  they  should 
have  this  rather  than  that  shape.  Indeed,  if  you  are  to  describe  as 
rational  all  the  ideals  which  science  pursues,  all  the  demands- 
which  reason  makes  of  what  is  presented  to  it,  you  must  take  the 
rational  as,  in  toto,  a  heap  of  contradictions.  Reason  demands, 
equally  the  identical,  the  singular,  the  continuous,  the  discrete,  the 
independent,  the  interrelated,  etc.  (see  ii.,  373,  for  M.  Meyerson's 
point).  My  own  view  is  that  the  explicit  formulation  of  each  of 
these  demands,  and  the  separate  following  of  it  to  its  end  with  the 
rigour  of  "  a  relentless  logic,"  endeavouring  to  use  it  as  the  guiding 
thread  through  the  labyrinth  of  reality,  is  an  essential  step  in  the 
process  of  refining  the  instruments  which  reason  uses  in  its  attempt 
to  discover  truth,  but  not  a  final  step  in  the  account  of  the  nature  of 
reason  itself.  What  exists  (nature)  is  presented  as  a  tangle  where- 
in reason  demands  "  fibres  "  (i.,  101 ;  ii.,  276,  285),  because  it  is  the 
nature  of  reason  to  demand  fibres.  But  reason's  own  "  fibres  "  are 
tangled  and  are  disentangled  by  itself  only  one  by  one ;  and  the 
process  of  disentangling  them  is  a  process  of  dissection  performed 
by  first  dimly  discerning  a  fibre  in  reason  itself,  and  then  endeavour- 
ing to  see  the  whole  of  nature  as  built  up  entirely  on  the  basis  of 
this  fibre.  All  this  however  is  only  dissection :  reason  is  not  a* 
mere  sum  of  fibres  but  a  whole  in  which  the  fibres  are  inter-related 
and  in  which  they  modify  one  another. 

Again,  while  I  should  say  that  the  explicit  account  of  the  nature 
of  reason  as  disentangled  at  any  date  is  to  be  found  in  the  Logic  of 
that  date,  I  should  not  agree  that  any  logic  could  be  final  until 
complete  knowledge  of  the  Universe  was  reached.  Man's  reason, 
M.  Meyerson  says,  is  completely  rational  (ii.,  307) ;  but  if  that  were 
true,  there  ought  to  be  something,  at  least  in  the  realm  of  concepts,, 
which  actually  did,  here  and  now,  completely  satisfy  that  part  of 
man's  nature  which  M.  Meyerson  calls  his  reason.  But  in  fact 
there  is  nothing  of  this  kind.  What  there  is,  is  something  which 
it  is  felt  would  satisfy  a  part  of  man's  nature  if  man  could  com- 
pletely comprehend  existence  by  its  help.  The  contemplation  of 
pure  identity  does  not  bring  satisfaction  ;  pure  identity  is  rather  a 
demand  which  brings  dissatisfaction  with  what  existence  presents, 
an  ideal  which  would  satisfy  if  it  could  be  realised  in  existence. 
Complete  rationality,  I  feel,  is  rather  an  ideal  to  be  attained  in  the 
far  away  future  ;  and  an  ideal  which  describes  what  not  a  part,  but 
the  whole  of  man's  nature,  is  striving  towards.  The  process  of 


EMILE  MEYEESON,  De  I' Explication  dans  les  Sciences.     517 

attaining  it  demands  that  man  should  formulate  with  all  rigour 
what  he  has  so  far  attained  of  it,  and  endeavour  to  follow  out  its 
consequences  relentlessly  in  thought  and  cautiously  in  action. 
For  life  demands  to  be  allowed  more  freedom ;  and  the  conflict 
resulting  is  equally  a  part  of  the  process. 

To  M.  Meyerson's  argument  that  reason  has  not  changed  we  can 
apply  his  own  method.  His  own  investigation  into  the  rational 
processes  followed  by  science  was  compelled  to  postulate  that  those 
processes  be  regarded  as  identical  with  those  of  the  present  day, 
because  otherwise  he  would  have  no  key  to  the  understanding  of 
them ;  but  he  was  equally  compelled,  in  his  investigation,  to  have 
recourse  to  the  notion  that  much  was  only  implicit  in  the  processes 
as  manifested  in  the  infancy  of  science,  which  became  explicit 
later  on.  Following  his  own  method,  we  shall  see  there  a  confession 
of  the  partial  insuccess  of  the  postulate  on  the  basis  of  which  the 
whole  investigation  proceeded  ;  but  we  shall  recognise  that  this 
was  inevitable,  and  that  the  investigation  could  take  no  other 
course,  in  its  initial  stage.  But  M.  Meyerson  has  done  his  work 
so  well  that  even  those  who  differ  from  him  in  his  view  of  what  is 
completely  rational  will  have  little  to  change  in  his  description  of 
scientific  processes. 

We  have  left  no  space  to  deal  with  the  profound  discussion  of 
the  relation  between  science  and  philosophy  in  Book  IV.,  and  our 
mention  of  Book  III.  has  been  all  too  scant ;  but  there  is  so  much 
in  M.  Meyerson's  volumes  that  we  cannot  hope  to  do  justice  in  a 
few  pages  even  to  his  main  topics.  As  before  in  Identify  et  Realite, 
there  is  a  rich  gleaning  in  the  Appendices. 

LEONAKD   KUSSELL. 


VII.— NEW  BOOKS. 

The  Greek  Tradition  from  the  Death  of  Socrates  to  the  Council  of  Chal- 
cedon,  Vol.  i.  The  Religion  of  Plato.  By  PAUL  ELMER  MORE. 
Princeton  University  Press  ;  London,  Humphrey  Milford,  1921.  Pp. 
xii,  352. 

THE  first  duty  of  a  reviewer  must  be  to  thank  Mr.  More  for  having  given 
us  so  fascinating  a  first  volume,  and  to  express  the  hope  that  he  may  be 
able  to  complete  the  task  he  has  set  before  him  in  a  reasonable  time.  For 
the  present  reviewer,  the  second  duty  must  be  to  express  his  hearty 
sympathy  with  Mr.  More's  general  purpose  as  laid  down  in  his  Preface. 
The  points  on  which  the  Preface  lays  stress  are  these  :  There  is  a  continuous 
tradition  of  the  spiritual  life,  presumably  derived  from  Socrates,  of  which 
Plato's  writings  are  the  truest  expression  ;  this  tradition  dominates  Greek 
thought,  though,  as  Mr.  More  holds,  it  has  been  dangerously  perverted  in 
its  later  forms  ;  from  Greek  philosophy  it  passes  into  the  Greek  fathers. 
In  fact,  the  Christian  Church,  rather  than  the  Neo-Platonists,  is  the 
legitimate  heir  of  Plato,  and  there  is  thus  a  single  uniform  development 
from  Socrates,  or  at  any  rate  from  the  earliest  work  of  Plato,  to  the  com- 
pletion of  the  formulation  of  the  Christian  faith  at  Chalcedon.  The  great 
truth  which  finds  its  expression  in  this  development  is  that  the  human 
spirit  itself  is  "  dual,"  an  inhabitant  of  the  eternal  and  the  temporal  realms 
at  once,  and  that  all  worthy  living  is  based  on  the  principle  of  subordinating 
the  merely  temporal  in  a  man's  self  (the  "flesh,"  as  St.  Paul  calls  it),  to 
the  eternal  (the  "  spirit  ").  It  is  just  this  great  conviction  which  our  world 
to-day  seems  in  danger  of  losing,  and  therefore,  for  the  sake  of  the  world's 
salvation,  it  is  imperative  to  bid  thoughtful  men  return  to  the  literature 
in  which  the  Greek  and  Christian  truth  is  most  plainly  and  emphatically 
preached,  from  the  Phaedo  down  to  Gregory  of  Nyssa  and  Chrysostom. 

In  all  these  fundamental  points  the  writer  of  the  present  notes  feels 
himself  wholly  at  one  with  Mr.  More.  There  are  matters  in  which  he 
cannot  see  altogether  eye  to  eye  with  his  author,  but  in  his  own  opinion 
these,  important  as  some  of  them  are  to  a  complete  estimate  of  Plato's 
philosophy,  are  secondary  in  a  study  of  Plato's  religion  and  rule  of  life, 
and,  in  some  cases,  may  be  reduced  after  all  to  mere  questions  of  the 
emphasis  to  be  laid  on  a  particular  strain  in  the  Platonic  dialogues.  The 
rest  of  this  notice  will  necessarily  be  largely  taken  up  with  the  raising  of 
doubts  about  these  points  of  difference,  but  I  should  like  to  make  it  clear 
beyond  all  question  that  I  fully  sympathise  with  Mr.  More's  central 
position  and  that  I  am  keenly  alive  to  the  real  beauty  and  literary  charm 
of  the  style  in  which  he  presents  it.  I  am  the  more  anxious  to  do  this 
that,  rightly  or  wrongly,  I  found  much  to  disagree  with  in  Mr.  More's 
preliminary  work  Platonism  and  its  presentment  of  Socrates. 

Now  to  say  something  on  the  matters  where,  rightly  or  wrongly,  I  find 
it  difficult  to  agree  with  Mr.  More,  and  would  respectfully  suggest  to  him 
that  he  might  perhaps  reconsider  his  utterances.  The  most  important  of 
these  is  his  insistence  upon  regarding  the  Platonic  philosophy,  as  well  as 


NEW  BOOKS.  519 

the  Platonic  religion,  as  "dualistic".  As  to  the  point  from  which  Mr. 
More  takes  his  departure,  he  is,  indeed,  clearly  in  the  right.  If  Plato  and 
Christianity  are  to  be  believed,  there  is  a  fundamental  duality  in  the 
human  soul  ;  every  soul  of  man  is  a  denizen  of  two  worlds  at  once,  and 
"  salvation"  means  definitely  rising  from  the  pursuit  of  the  ephemeral  to 
the  pursuit  of  the  eternal.  And  I  further  agree  that  most  contemporary 
ethics  and  a  great  deal  of  contemporary  speculative  philosophy  are  vapid 
and  mischievous  precisely  because  they  will  not  recognise  this  division  of 
the  soul  against  itself.  But  it  is  another  question  whether  this  duality 
in  unity  which  we  find  in  ourselves  justifies  an  ultimate  "  dualism  "  in 
philosophy.  For  the  unity  of  the  person  in  whom  the  duality  is  found 
is  precisely  what  makes  the  tragic  element  in  the  soul's  life.  I  think  Mr. 
More  has  been  led  into  exaggeration  on  the  point  by  a  bias  against  the  cheap 
"  monisms  "  of  the  Spinozistic  type  or  the  type  of  an  Hegelianism  inter- 
preted in  a  Spinozistic  sense.  For  my  own  part,  I  fully  agree  with  him 
that  this  sort  of  monism  is  the  worst  and  most  superficial  of  philosophies, 
and  am  wholly  on  his  side  in  his  vigorous  protests  against  the  interpreta- 
tions which  read  "  immanenfcisrn "  and  "pantheism  "  into  Plato.  But  I 
do  not  see  that  there  is  warrant  for  ascribing  to  Plato  a  dualism  which 
seriously  sets  up  two  cosmic  principles.  Still  less  do  I  think  Plato  would 
have  agreed  with  Mr.  More's  "  irrationalism  "  and  distrust  of  logic.  I 
venture  to  believe  that  Plato  would  have  said  that  the  cure  for  the  kind  of 
rationalism  which  shuts  its  eyes  to  all  the  facts  that  will  not  fit  into  its 
preconceived  schemes  is  not  less  of  hard  logical  thinking,  but  more  of  it. 
Indeed,  this  seems  to  be  the  real  point  of  the  Parmenides,  where  the 
youthful  Socrates  is  warned  that  his  helplessness  in  the  face  of  criticism 
is  due  to  lack  of  the  indispensable  yvp.vaoria  in  just  this  so-called  "  useless  " 
dialectic.  I  do  not  think  Plato  shows  any  signs  of  the  impatience  Mr. 
More  feels  with  what  he  himself  calls  * '  metaphysic  "  and  describes  as  the 
attempt  to  rationalise  the  ultimate  how  and  why  of  things.  Plato  is,  to 
be  sure,  quite  alive  to  the  impossibility  of  achieving  finality  in  such  an 
attempt,  but  I  am  sure  that  he  holds  that  we  ought  to  do  the  best  we  can, 
because  there  really  is  an  intelligible  "ultimate  how  and  why,"  even 
if  our  mortal  eyes  are  holden  so  that  we  cannot  see  it. 

I  should  like  to  suggest  that  this  bias  against  "  metaphysic"  makes  Mr. 
More  unconsciously  unfair  to  Neo-Platonism.  When  he  complains  of  the 
mischief  done  by  Aristotle  (the  least  religious  of  great  Greek  philosophers), 
in  narrowing  down  "imitation  of  God"  to  the  "speculative  life,"  I 
wholly  sympathise,  and  I  am  moved  to  admiration  by  his  fine  pages  at  the 
end  of  the  book  on  Plato's  insistence  on  "  service,"  where  he  says  much 
which  I  have  always  tried  to  urge  upon  pupils  in  the  course  of  many 
years'  teaching.  But  the  hard  verdicts  passed,  for  example,  on  Plotinus 
seem  to  me  to  indicate  insufficient,  or  at  least  insufficiently  sympathetic, 
study.  Two  passages  are  particularly  singled  out  for  reprobation,  the 
famous  words  at  the  end  of  Ennead  VI.  about  the  flight  of  the  "  alone  to 
the  Alone,"  and  the  other  about  the  shedding  of  memories  of  earth  by 
the  "risen  "  soul.  I  doubt  if  they  will  bear  all  the  meaning  which  is  put 
upon  them.  As  for  the  "  flight,"  there  does  not  seem  to  me  any  evidence 
that  Plotinus  is  preaching  the  shallow  doctrine  of  the  "absorption  "  of 
our  personality  into  an  impersonal  absolute,  which  I  should  repudiate  as 
vehemently  as  Mr.  More  does.  I  take  him  to  be  actually  describing  a 
fact  of  experience  of  which  most  of  us  have  some  knowledge,  and  I  do  not 
really  believe  that  he  goes  beyond  what  Mr.  More  has  said  quite  beauti- 
fully himself  about  the  combination  of  detachment  and  attachment.  And 
it  S3ems  clear  to  me,  after  an  attentive  and  prolonged  study  of  the  leading 
Neo-Platonists,  that  their  actual  belief  was  quite  definitely  opposed  to 
anything  like  "  absorption  ".  Union  with  the  "  One  "  is  not  "absorption  " 


520  NEW   BOOKS. 

into  it ;  the  plurality  of  individual  immortal  souls  seems  to  me  just  as 
indispensable  to  the  Neo-Platonist  scheme  as  the  dependence  of  all  things 
on  the  "  One  ".  And  as  to  the  other  passage,  if  it  is  read  sympathetically, 
does  it  not  appear  as  a  justified  protest  against  the  triviality  of  spiritual- 
istic "messages  from  the  other  world,"  a  triviality  equally  obnoxious 
to  Mr.  More  himself  ?  I  suggest  that  Mr.  More  exaggerates  the  differ- 
ences between  Plotinus  and  Plato  by  not  allowing  enough  for  the  differences 
in  their  times.  After  all  Plotinus  led  the  life  not  of  a  cloistered  quietist 
but  of  a  man  pretty  fully  occupied  in  the  only  business  open  to  him,  and 
he  seems  to  have  been  fairly  shrewd  and  successful  even  in  the  matter  of 
looking  after  the  investments  of  hia  friends.  When  the  so-called  "in- 
activity "  of  philosophers  in  the  third  century  is  censured,  it  is  usually 
forgotten  that  their  activity,  when  they  got  their  chance,  a  century  later, 
under  Julian,  is  commonly  equally  censured  by  the  very  same  critics. 

I  dwell  on  the  point  partly  because  I  should  like  to  suggest  that  Mr. 
More  should  modify  his  admiration  for  Plutarch  as  a  guide  to  Plato's 
meaning.  I  think,  if  this  were  the  proper  place,  I  could  show  that 
Plutarch  has  definitely  led  him  astray  about  the  meaning  of  the  Timaeus, 
but  I  do  not  dwell  on  the  matter,  as  it,  after  all,  concerns  Plato's  science 
and  not  his  religion.  From  Plutarch  himself  we  learn  a  good  deal  about 
the  way  in  which  the  Timaeus  was  understood  by  Plato's  own  immediate 
pupil  Xenocrates,  and  by  Grantor  in  the  next  generation,  and  Plotinus,  I 
should  say,  stands  much  more  in  the  line  of  direct  development  from 
these  first  Platonists  than  Plutarch  does. 

I  may  mention,  as  a  set-off  to  these  doubts,  a  number  of  secondary 
points  where  I  am  delighted  to  find  Mr.  More  vigorously  championing 
what  seems  to  myself  the  only  true  interpretation.  I  am  glad  that  he 
will  have  no  truck  with  the  attempts  to  whittle  down  Plato's  express 
ascription  of  personality  to  God  and  of  immortality  to  the  individual 
human  soul.  I  am  sure  he  is  right  again  in  refusing  to  confound  Plato's 
God,  who  is  a  perfectly  good  soul,  with  the  system  of  el'S??,  and  I  quite 
agree  with  him  that  in  Plato's  treatment  the  eiSrj  are,  in  a  sense,  "above  " 
God.  (I  am  not  equally  satisfied  that  this  doctrine  is  one  in  which  we  can 
finally  acquiesce.  Orthodox  Christianity  takes  a  different  view  and  one 
which  seems  to  me  truer.  At  any  rate,  I  am  sure  Mr.  More  is  not  right 
when  he  argues  that,  as  a  consequence  of  not  putting  the  ei&j  above  God, 
orthodoxy  has  come  to  regard  moral  distinctions  as  arbitrarily  established 
by  God,  things  of  "mere  will,"  to  use  Cudworth's  language.  I  am  sure 
that  this  is  not  and  never  has  been  the  general  sense  of  the  Christian 
Church  ;  still  less  is  it  a  dogma  of  the  Faith.)  Again,  I  am  delighted  to 
see  that,  with  all  his  deference  to  Plutarch,  Mr.  More  will  have  nothing  to 
do  with  an  ' '  evil  world-soul  ".  (Yet  I  wish  he  had  not  read  astrology  into 
the  famous  passage  of  the  Laws.  A  careful  study  shows,  I  think,  that 
when  Plato  insists  on  the  existence  of  bad  souls  he  is  thinking  simply  of 
the  undeniable  fact  that  there  are  bad  men.  He  goes  on  at  once  to  ask 
whether  the  soul  which  "  manages  "  the  world  is  good  or  bad,  and  answers 
that  it  is  good.  Hence  I  do  not  believe  that  he  means  for  a  moment  to 
entertain  the  notion  that  there  is  real  disorder,  caused  by  "  malign  " 
souls  anywhere  in  the  "  heavens".  I  think  Mr.  More  might,  at  least,  re- 
consider his  own  interpretation.)  On  the  other  side,  I  feel  sure — I  am 
obliged  for  reasons  of  space  to  put  my  conclusions  more  dogmatically  than 
I  could  wish — that  it  is  a  mistake  to  interpret  the  dvdyKrj  and  x<*>Pa  °^  tfte 
Timaeus  as  symbols  for  the  "  dark,"  "  unreasonable  "  element  in  our  souls. 
The  Timaeus  is  concerned  with  science  as  well  as  with  religion,  and  what 
is  said  about  x^Pa  an^  avdyK-q  is  a  contribution  to  physics.  Aristotle  was 
quite  aware  of  this,  and  has  warned  us  that  the  doctrine  of  x^Pa  ^n  ^ne 
Timaeus  is  an  analysis  not  fully  agreeing  with  that  given  by  Plato  himself 


NEW  BOOKS.  521 

in  the  Academy.  This  Platonic  analysis,  described  by  Aristotle,  is  on  the 
face  of  it  a  piece  of  geometrical  physics,  not  a  contribution  to  religion.  As 
for  avdyKrj  in  the  Timaeus,  it  demands  a  very  careful  study,  and  cannot 
be  approached  better  than  from  consideration  of  Proclus's  discussion  of 
the  meaning  of  dvdyKrj  in  his  commentary  on  the  Republic.  I  will  only 
remark  here  that  the  dvdyKr)  of  the  Timaeus  cannot  well  ba  "chance," 
since  its  special  function  is  to  be  the  "  under-strapper  "  (vTrTjperrjs)  of 
intelligence.  But  the  true  interpretation  of  the  Timaeus  is  a  topic  which 
could  only  be  treated  successfully  in  an  elaborate  clause-by-clause  com- 
mentary. 

One  naturally  awaits  Mr.  More's  further  volumes  with  some  impatience. 
There  is  one  dark  saying  which  I  hope  they  will  make  clear.  I  do  not  see 
that  the  dogmatic  definition  of  the  persona  Christi  really  has  anything  to 
do  with  the  "  dualism  "  in  the  human  soul.  The  problem  decided  at 
Chalcedon  did  not  concern  the  human  soul  of  our  Lord  at  all.  It  had  to 
do  with  the  co-existence  in  one  person  of  a  complete  humanity  and  com- 
plete Deity.  But,  no  doubt,  Mr.  More  will  make  the  connexion  of 
thought  more  apparent  in  due  time,  though  I  confess  that  at  present  1 
find  it  obscure. 

A.  E.  TAYLOR. 

An  Introduction  to  Philosophy.     By  WILHELM  WINDELBAND.     Translated 
by  JOSEPH  McCABE.     London  :  Fisher  Unwin,  1921.     Pp.  365. 

Speaking  of  previous  '  Introductions  '  to  philosophy  Windelband  says 
that  "  by  far  the  most  scientific  and  instructive  work  "  is  that  of  Kiilpe, 
and  it  would  perhaps  not  be  unfair  to  describe  the  present  work  as  similar 
in  character  to  Kiilpe's  though  written  on  a  more  ample  scale  and  there- 
fore in  a  fuller  and  less  severe  style.  A  brief  outline  of  the  scheme  and 
contents  of  the  book  will  show  how  far  the  comparison  is  justified. 

The  task  of  philosophy,  according  to  Windelband,  is  to  subject  the 
working  assumptions  which  are  made  in  practical  life  and  in  the  special 
sciences  to  a  critical  examination.  The  aim  of  an  'Introduction  to 
Philosophy '  accordingly  is  to  show  how  in  the  course  of  such  an  investi- 
gation certain  fundamental  problems  inevitably  present  themselves  and 
what  are  the  main  lines  along  which  a  solution  of  these  problems  has 
been  sought.  The  fundamental  problems  of  philosophy  are  divided  into 
the  two  main  classes  of  Theoretical  problems,  on  the  one  hand,  and  Prac- 
tical or  rather  Axiological  (problems  of  value),  on  the  other.  But  we  are 
warned  that  this  division  cannot  be  rigidly  maintained,  and  Windelband 
is  inclined  in  fact  to  lay  great  stress  on  the  part  which  ideas  of  value  play 
in  philosophy.  "Metaphysics  is  the  hypos tatisation  of  ideals  "  (p.  40). 

After  a  preliminary  section  on  the  distinction  between  reality  and 
appearance — the  distinction  which  necessarily  provokes  philosophical 
reflexion — the  theoretical  problems  are  divided  into  three  groups :  ontic, 
genetic,  and  noetic.  The  '  Ontic '  problems  are  discussed  under  the  three 
heads  of  Substance,  Quantity  of  Being,  and  Qualitative  Determinations  of 
Reality.  The  section l  on  Substance  first  deals  with  the  notion  of  thing 
or  substance  generally,  then  contrasts  the  tendencies  to  seek  true  sub- 
stance alternatively  in  the  universal  or  in  the  individual,  and  lastly  con- 
siders the  difficulties  of  conceiving  the  essential  unity  of  the  substance  in 
relation  to  its  diverse  properties  or  states.  The  section  on  Quantity 
discusses  first  the  opposition  between  systems  of  Monism  or  Singularism 

1  In  an  English  book  the  sections  would  rather  be  chapters.  The  section 
on  Substance,  e.g.,  runs  to  25  pp. 


522  NEW   BOOKS. 

and  systems  of  Pluralism,  and  second  the  problems  connected  with  the 
contrast  of  Finite  and  Infinite  as  regards  space,  time,  and  existence 
generally.  The  section  on  Quality  discusses  the  distinction  between 
primary  and  secondary  qualities,  the  reference  to  mind  involved  in  the 
distinction,  the  nature  of  mind,  and  then  the  fundamental  opposition 
between  mind  and  matter,  together  with  the  philosophical  systems — 
Spiritualism,  Materialism  and  Dualism — whose  character  depends  on 
their  treatment  of  this  opposition. 

The  chapter  on  Genetic  problems  deals  in  the  first  section  with  succes- 
sion in  time  generally,  in  the  second  with  problems  of  causality,  in  the 
third  with  the  opposition  between  mechanism  and  teleology,  and  in  the 
fourth  with  the  relation  of  body  and  mind. 

The  chapter  on  Noetic  problems  may  be  described  as  a  short  general 
account  of  theories  of  knowledge  in  connexion  with  such  topics  as  the 
criterion  of  truth,  the  origin  and  validity  of  knowledge,  and  the  types  of 
science.  In  a  section  on  '  The  Object  of  Knowledge '  Windelband  seems 
to  permit  himself  a  more  direct  statement  of  his  own  views  than  he  does 
as  a  rule  elsewhere. 

Part  II.  is  devoted  to  the  Axiological  problems,  and,  after  an  intro- 
ductory section  on  the  psychological  and  normative  aspects  of  valuation 
in  general,  deals  in  successive  chapters  with  Ethical,  ^Esthetic,  and 
Religious  problems.  The  scheme  of  the  first  chapter  is  indicated  in  the 
following  quotation.  "  The  subject  of  moral  conduct  is  partly  the  indi- 
vidual, partly  the  social  community,  and  partly  the  species  in  its  historical 
evolution.  Hence  we  get  the  three  sections  of  practical  philosophy  which 
we  may  distinguish  as  morality,  social  science,  and  the  philosophy  of 
history  "  (p.  219).  The  first  section  accordingly  deals  with  ethical  prob- 
lems in  the  narrower  sense  of  the  term,  and  considers  successively  the 
content,  the  knowledge  or  psychological  source,  the  sanction,  and  the 
motive,  of  morality.  Under  the  first  head  a  brief  criticism  of  types  of 
ethical  theory  is  given,  and  the  section  concludes  with  a  few  pages  on  the 
freedom  of  the  will.  The  second  section  deals  with  the  relation  of  the 
individual  will  to  the  General  Will  of  the  community,  the  various  types 
of  community  such  as  the  family,  the  State,  and  the  Church,  the  problem 
of  their  function  or  value,  and  finally  with  the  philosophy  of  law  and  of 
the  State.  The  third  section  deals  with  personality  as  the  vital  factor  in 
history — "what  constitutes  the  power  of  the  significant  personality  is 
that  it  develops  superpersonal  values  in  itself  and  externalises  them  " 
(p.  287) — with  the  idea  of  humanity,  the  nature  of  historical  progress,  and 
the  ultimate  or  metaphysical  significance  of  history. 

The  chapter  on  '  ^Esthetic  Problems  '  has  three  sections  entitled  respec- 
tively 'The  Concept  of  the  ^Esthetic,'  'The  Beautiful'  and  'Art,'  but 
the  whole  chapter  covers  only  some  twenty  pages  and  may  be  passed  over 
without  further  remark.  The  concluding  chapter  on  '  Religious  Problems ' 
is  also  somewhat  meagre  and  disappointing,  especially  when  we  consider 
that  it  is  in  the  sphere  of  religion  that  we  meet  our  final  question  as  to 
the  relation  of  the  axiological  to  the  theoretical  problems.  The  first 
section  deals  with  the  distinctive  character  of  religion  in  general  and 
maintains  that  religion  has  no  special  province  of  values  such  as  science, 
art,  and  morality  have.  "It  consists  in  the  metaphysical  tincture  and 
relation  which  all  these  values  may  assume.  Religion  would  be  deprived  of 
its  universal  significance  if  the  sacred  were  marked  off  from  the  other 
cultural  provinces  as  a  special  section  of  the  life  of  values  "  (p.  328).  The 
second  section,  entitled  '  The  Truth  of  Religion,'  gives  a  brief  account  of 
the  arguments  for  immortality  and  the  existence  of  God.  The  ^  final 
section  on  '  Reality  and  Value  '  insists  on  the  dualism  of  '  ought '  and 
' is,'  of  value  and  reality,  as  one  which  we  cannot  rise  above.  "The  fact 


NEW  BOOKS.  523 

of  valuation  necessarily  implies  a  dualism  of  the  valuable  and  valueless 
in  reality.  This  subtle  truth,  which  is  easily  overlooked,  may  be  traced 
in  the  meaning  of  the  two  attitudes  which  we  find  opposing  each  other 
under  the  names  of  optimism  and  pessimism  "  (p.  352).  But  the  dualism 
out  of  which  these  opposed  doctrines  spring  is  one  which  we  cannot 
resolve.  "  From  the  very  nature  of  the  case  this  final  problem  is  in- 
soluble. It  is  the  sacred  mystery,  marking  the  limits  of  our  nature  and 
our  knowledge.  We  must  be  content  to  remain  there  and  to  recognise 
that  here,  at  this  inmost  point  of  life,  our  knowledge  and  understanding 
can  reach  no  further  than  the  other  side  of  our  being,  the  will.  For  the 
will  the  duality  of  value  [and]  reality  is  the  indispensable  condition  of  its 
activity.  If  value  and  reality  were  identical,  there  would  be  no  will  and 
no  event.  All  would  remain  motionless  in  a  state  of  eternal  completion. 
The  innermost  meaning  of  time  is  the  inalienable  difference  between  what 
is  and  what  ought  to  be ;  and  because  this  difference,  which  reveals 
itself  in  our  will,  constitutes  the  fundamental  condition  of  human  life, 
our  knowledge  can  never  get  beyond  it  to  a  comprehension  of  its  origin  " 
(pp.  358-359). 

Windelband  claims  in  the  Preface  that  his  work  is  not  an  introduction 
to  a  particular  philosophical  system  but  '  *  makes  a  very  wide  survey  of 
all  the  possibilities  in  the  way  of  solutions ".  While  granting  that 
4<  naturally,  it  is  based  upon  the  author's  personal  view,"  he  tells  us  that 
"this  will  not  be  pressed,  or  suffered  to  influence  the  author's  judgment 
in  appraising  other  systems  of  thought".  And  on  the  whole  his  claim  is 
justified,  for  he  is  usually  careful  to  state  as  fairly  and  objectively  as  he 
can  the  arguments  and  difficulties  on  both  sides  of  any  controverted 
question.  But  he  seems  sometimes  to  be  unaware  that  he  is  making 
large  assumptions  and  taking  propositions  as  self-evident  that  are  far 
from  being  so.  One  or  two  examples  will  suffice.  "The  more  a 
personality  can  be  described  or  defined,  the  less  is  its  individuality  and 
originality  "  (p.  64).  "  The  successive  acts  of  consciousness,  of  which 
the  individual  experience  consists,  are  discrete  or  discontinuous  elements  " 
(p.  123).  "The  self-knowledge  of  the  soul  is  ...  the  only  knowledge 
in  which  we  can  be  convinced  beyond  doubt  of  the  likeness  between 
knowledge  and  its  object "  (p.  193).  In  one  set  of  utterances  the  author 
displays  a  curiously  superficial  cynicism.  "The  morality  of  enlightened 
interest  ...  is  the  morality  of  actual  life  :  the  theory  that  the  great 
majority  of  men  have  held  in  all  ages  and  will  continue  to  hold"  (p.  228). 
"  We  may  be  confident  that  what  seems  to  be  morality  in  the  case  of  the 
great  majority  of  men  is  no  more  than  legality  based  on  fear  and  hope 
with  respect  to  various  authorities"  (p.  245).  "Personality  again  has 
various  degrees.  The  great  majority,  who  seem  to  be  there  merely  for 
the  propagation  of  the  race,  have  only  a  potential  personality  "  (p.  281). 

To  estimate  the  value  of  the  book  accurately  is  not  easy.  As  the  work 
of  a  prominent  historian  of  philosophy  it  is  of  course  written  out  of  a  full 
knowledge  and  contains  plenty  good  and  interesting  matter.  But  for 
one  thing  it  is  not  clear  for  what  class  of  readers  the  book  is  really 
designed.  It  is  not  well  adapted  either  to  the  needs  of  the  student  who 
is  just  beginning  his  study  of  philosophy  or  again  to  those  of  the  merely 
general  reader,  inasmuch  as  it  tends  to  assume  too  much  previous  know- 
ledge. What,  for  instance,  are  such  readers  likely  to  make  of  a  passage 
like  the  following  ?  "  [Kant]  found  that  theoretical  reason  threatened  to 
call  into  question,  not  only  the  knowableness,  but  even  the  thiukableness 
— that  is  to  say,  the  metaphysical-  reality — of  the  suprasensible,  or  at 
least  to  make  it  entirely  problematical ;  then  his  practical  reason  '  realises  ' 
the  suprasensible,  and  inspires  a  conviction  of  the  higher  world  of  ethical- 
religious  metaphysics  lurking  behind  the  appearances  "  (p.  41).  To  the 


524  NEW  BOOKS. 

more  advanced  student  the  value  of  the  book  is  naturally  lessened  by  the 
almost  inevitable  circumstances  that  the  ground  covered  is  often  very 
familiar  and  the  treatment,  in  spite  of  the  fairly  large  scale  of  the  book, 
summary  and  unsatisfying.  On  the  other  hand  he  will  no  doubt  find 
many  interesting  and  suggestive  surveys  of  the  topics  of  philosophical 
controversy.  It  is  a  drawback,  however,  from  this  point  of  view  that  no 
detailed  references  to  the  literature  are  given  which  would  enable  the 
student  to  follow  up  a  subject  for  himself.  Probably  the  book  would  be 
of  most  use  to  the  student  or  general  reader  who  had  obtained  some 
knowledge  of  the  history  of  philosophy  and  wanted  to  take  stock  of  the 
results.  But  I  question  whether  even  for  this  purpose  the  plan  followed 
in  the  book  is  a  good  one. 

It  is  no  doubt  a  very  difficult  thing  to  write  a  good  Introduction  to 
philosophy,  and  the  difficulties  are  to  a  large  extent  inherent  in  the  nature 
of  the  case.  But  I  do  not  think  that  Windelband's  plan  meets  them  in 
the  best  way.  In  the  second  part  of  the  book,  where  he  is  dealing  with 
the  Ethical,  ^Esthetic,  and  Religious  problems,  he  is  simply  traversing 
in  a  rapid,  and  necessarily  partial,  way  the  ground  of  certain  special  sub- 
jects. Of  the  three  chapters  the  best  is  that  on  Ethical  problems,  but  the 
student  would  probably  always  be  better  served  by  going  to  the  special 
treatises  devoted  to  the  respective  subjects.  In  the  first  part  of  the  book 
the  chapters  on  the  Genetic  and  Noetic  problems  are  the  most  interesting 
and  profitable  to  read,  because  the  sections  have  some  definite  sequence 
and  deal  with  a  connected  series  of  problems.  The  chapter  on  *  Ontic ' 
problems,  on  the  other  hand,  with  its  three  sections  on  Substance, 
Quantity,  and  Quality,  seems  to  me  to  adopt  a  radically  bad  method, 
which  leads  to  artificial  separations  and  conjunctions,  and  prevents  the 
reader  from  gaining  any  broad  view  of  the  types  of  metaphysical  theory 
which  have  played  a  leading  part  in  the  history  of  philosophy.  The 
author  splits  up  problems  in  Kiilpe's  fashion  and  with  even  more  un- 
fortunate results.  Thus  under  the  head  of  Substance  we  have  an 
opposition  between  Universalism  and  Individualism,  and  under  the  head 
of  Quantity  very  much  the  same  opposition  with  the  new  designation  of 
Monism  or  Singularism  versus  Pluralism.  But  Dualism,  Spiritualism, 
and  IV  aterialism  are  discussed  in  the  section  on  Qualitative  Determina- 
tions of  Reality.  We  have  only  to  take  a  philosophy  like  that  of  Leibniz 
to  see  how  misleading  all  this  is.  To  put  his  Spiritualism  and  Pluralism 
and  Individualism  under  separate  heads  as  answers  to  separate  problems 
is  simply  to  destroy  the  systematic  connexion  which  is  the  essence  of  a 
philosophy — surely  a  poor  way  of  introducing  the  reader  to  "  the  science 
of  philosophising  ".  Whatever  its  merits  in  detail,  the  chapter  as  a  whole 
can  hardly  be  otherwise  than  puzzling  and  confusing  to  the  ordinary 
student  or  general  reader,  and  unfortunately  it  is  in  one  way  the  most 
important  chapter  in  the  book,  dealing  as  it  does  with  the  fundamental 
types  of  ontological  theory. 

Not  having  the  German  original  for  comparison,  I  cannot  speak  with 
confidence  as  to  the  merits  of  the  translation.  It  seems  as  a  rule  to  read 
well  enough,  at  least  to  serve  its  purpose.  On  the  other  hand,  not  to 
speak  of  mere  slips,  it  makes  mistakes  which  are  obvious  even'  in  the 
English  version.  The  following  are  some  examples  from  the  early 
sections.  The  English  word  *  antinomianism '  has  no  such  connexion 
with  philosophical  antinomies  as  the  German  original  doubtless  has.  In 
a  passage  that  refers  to  Leibniz's  monadology  we  are  told  that  * '  the 
universe  is  unity  in  plurality  in  the  sense  that  each  of  its  parts  is  equal 
to  the  whole  and  therefore  to  all  the  others  "  (p.  85).  The  original  must 
surely  speak  of  resemblance  or  correspondence  here,  not  of  equality.  In 
the  statement  that  "the  unity  of  mass  is  in  all  cases  arbitrary  and 


NEW  BOOKS.  525 

conventional"  (p.  88)  one  suspects  that  "unity  of  mass"  should  be 
"  unit  of  measurement". 

The  German  original  was  apparently  published  in  1914,  but  owing  to 
the  war  it  is  probably  little  known  here,  and  the  English  version  will 
therefore  be  specially  useful. 

H.  BARKER. 

A  History  of  Psychology.  By  GEORGE  SIDNEY  BRETT.  London :  Allen 
&  Unwin,  Ltd.  New  York  :  The  Macmillan  Company,  1921. 
Vol.  II.,  Mediseval  and  Early  Modern  Period.  Pp.  394.  Vol.  III., 
Modern  Period.  Pp.  322. 

These  two  volumes  complete  a  history  of  which  the  first  volume,  History 
of  Psychology :  Ancient  and  Patristic,  was  published  as  far  back  as  1912  ; 
Prof.  Brett  is  to  be  congratulated  on  the  result.  The  history  of 
psychology  is  an  exceptionally  difficult  theme  to  handle.  Psychology  is 
not  yet  a  branch  of  science,  and  it  is  no  longer  a  branch  of  philosophy. 
It  is  still  engaged  in  working  out  its  own  salvation.  In  discussions,  even 
of  the  most  purely  "  experimental "  data,  there  are  constant  references 
to  names  and  theories  of  earlier  psychologists,  and  there  has  been  great 
need  for  a  handbook  giving  a  sketch  of  the  more  important  writers  on 
psychology, — their  works,  their  attitude  on  the  fundamental  questions, 
and  their  contributions  to  the  progress  of  the  subject.  This  need  the 
present  work  supplies  ;  but  it  does  much  more  than  that.  With  all  its 
scholarship  and  its  science,  there  is  a  vein  of  enthusiasm  and  romance 
running  through  the  work,  and  we  agree  with  Prof.  Brett  that  it  is 
"  worth  while  to  contemplate  the  spectacle  of  a  quest  which  has  called 
forth  from  the  beginning  of  time  the  most  passionate  desires,  the  most 
distorted  theories,  the  most  bitter  disputes,  and  the  most  refined  thought 
possible  to  the  human  being  ".  If  this  were  the  history  of  a  science,  it 
would  be  the  chronicle  of  discoveries  of  fact,  of  the  forming  of  theories 
and  their  gradual  replacement  by  others,  as  experiment  or  practical 
application  showed  their  errors.  But  there  are  few  facts  of  mind 
to  record,  and  the  theories  are  presented  here  as  successive  variations 
upon  a  comparatively  small  number  of  themes.  In  other  words  what  we 
have  is  the  history  of  a  part  of  philosophy,  and  of  the  gradual,  as  yet 
incomplete,  detachment  of  the  part  from  the  whole,  and  its  struggle  for 
independence.  Questions  of  "  presuppositions,"  methods  of  inquiry,  and 
methods  of  interpretation,  bulk  far  more  largely  than  those  of  facts,  of 
laws,  or  of  practical  applications. 

Mr.  Brett's  general  plan  for  the  work  is  to  give  for  each  period  first  the 
state  of  the  sciences  which  influenced  psychology,  then  the  state  of 
psychology  itself  during  that  period,  then  the  influence  of  psychology 
upon  other  sciences,  and  its  general  applications.  But  it  is  only  occasion- 
ally (e.g.,  in  Part  III.  of  Vol.  II.)  that  he  is  able  to  carry  out  this  scheme  ; 
mostly  the  order  of  time  dominates,  but  occasionally  a  separate  topic  is 
worked  out  by  itself,  and  the  geographical  order  also  intervenes.  In  the 
second  volume,  the  divisions  are — Part  I.,  The  Background  of  Mediaeval 
Thought  (Theology,  Scholarship,  Tradition) ;  Part  II.,  Mediaeval  Doctrines 
(the  Beginnings  of  Mediaeval  Psychology  in  the  ninth,  and  up  to  the  end 
of  the  sixteenth  century) ;  Part  III. ,  From  the  Sixteenth  to  the 
Eighteenth  Century  ;  and  Part  IV.,  The  Eighteenth  Century. 

As  we  approach  modern  times,  the  space  given  to  each  century  increases. 
The  nineteenth  century  has  the  third  volume  to  itself  ;  Part  I. ,  The  Age 
of  Transition  (Scottish  School,  Fries,  Herbart,  Beneke,  Schopenhauer, 
etc.),  Part  II.,  Modern  Psychology — "General  Scientific  Tendencies," 


526  NEW  BOOKS. 

"  From  Fechner  to  Wundt,"  "  Representative  Types  of  Theory,"  "  British 
Psychology  in  the  Nineteenth  Century,"  "The  Progress  of  Psychology," 
and  "The  Scope  of  Modern  Psychology,"  being  the  titles  of  the  successive 
chapters. 

The  style  has  a  distinction,  and  clearness,  with  frequent  flashes  of 
humour,  which  make  the  volumes  easy  to  read,  in  spite  of  the  unavoid- 
able tediousness  of  some  of  the  topics.  Of  a  certain  French  treatise  on 
the  faculties  of  the  soul  we  are  told  that  it  "  reached  a  second  edition  in 
1865,  and  was  henceforth  regarded  as  the  catechism  of  this  school 
[Jouffroy's]  and  its  most  complete  condemnation"  III.,  p.  24  :  of  Mansel, 
that  "his  defects  were  not  personal,  they  were  the  excellences  of  his 
generation"  ibid.,  p.  28.  The  only  defect,  if  it  is  one,  is  the  constant 
tracing  of  views  and  theories  back  to  Aristotle,  Plato  or  Plotinus.  A 
theory  is  not  explained  when  it  is  said  to  be  Aristotle  over  again  ;  similarly, 
there  is  perhaps  too  much  said  of  "anticipations  "  of  modern  views,  e.g., 
in  Erigena,  in  Duns  Scotus,  etc. 

Neither  in  psychology  nor  in  philosophy  are  there  any  real  anticipa- 
tions ;  Aristotle's  psychology  may  have  had  a  direct  influence  when 
it  was  really  studied;  but  this  it  very  seldom  was.  The  apparent 
similarity  of  so  many  views — e.g.,  those  on  the  activity  of  the  soul, 
the  importance  of  feeling,  etc.,  to  those  of  Aristotle,  is  irrelevant  in 
a  genuine  history ;  the  formula  may  be  the  same,  but  almost  certainly 
what  is  meant  in  each  age,  by  such  a  term  as  "activity"  is  something 
•quite  specific,  and  different  from  Aristotle's  meaning.  As  an  example — 
of  Albertus  and  Aquinas  it  is  said  (II.,  p.  116),  "  We  have  here 'already 
the  cleft  between  mind  and  matter  which  Descartes  will  be  found 
developing  later  ;  we  have,  too,  the  Cartesian  principle  of  union  through 
God ;  and,  at  the  same  time  there  is  more  than  one  suggestion  of  that 
later  Aristotelianism  which  Kant  so  ingeniously  elaborated".  I  am  not 
sure  that  Mr.  Brett  appreciates  the  extraordinary  skill  and  delicacy  with 
which  the  great  scholastics  were  working  out,  for  their  own  immediate 
needs  in  the  first  instance,  but  also  for  all  time  to  come,  a  language  which 
would  be  adequate  to  express  the  deeper  aspects  of  the  soul  to  which  men 
were  slowly  penetrating.  No  doubt  there  is  an  attractiveness  in  the  dis- 
covery that  something  very  like  Wundt's  theory  of  Apperception,  and 
James'  fringe  of  consciousness,  appears  in  Duns  Scotus,  or  that  Associa- 
tionism  dawned  for  a  brief  and  ineffective  moment  in  the  minds  of  Witelo 
and  Roger  Bacon,  and  that  subconscious  factors  in  mind  were  appealed  to 
again  and  again,  from  Augustine  onwards,  before  the  theory  reached  its 
height  in  modern  psychology.  But  it  does  not  really  explain  how  each 
writer  came  to  hold  his  particular  form  of  the  theory,  and  at  one  particular 
period  in  history. 

In  the  third  volume  (p.  130)  Mr.  Brett  discusses  the  idea  of  a  "  psycho- 
logical "  account  of  writers  and  their  systems — "  Whether  that  means  the 
consequent  rejection  of  all  such  systems,  as  exploded  fictions,  is  quite 
another  question.  To  give  a  psychological  explanation  of  a  course  of 
thought  is  not  the  same  thing  as  proving  it  a  form  of  madness."  Pro- 
bably, if  it  could  be  done,  a  psychological  account  of  systems  would  really 
give  the  most  satisfactory  history,  taking  into  consideration  both  the 
tradition  and  the  social  environment  of  the  writers.  The  views  held  by 
psychologists  about  the  nature  and  structure  of  the  mind,  its  relation  to 
the  brain,  etc. ,  have,  down  to  our  own  times,  been  decided  by  their  view  of 
life  and  its  meaning,  their  philosophy.  "  It  is  an  open  question  whether 
a  psychologist  can  be  an  idealist  or  a  realist.  He  should  perhaps  be 
simply  a  psychologist.  But  apart  from  collectors  of  details  and  writers 
of  monographs,  history  has  failed  to  produce  a  psychologist  who  was  not 
a  philosopher  of  some  kind  :  and  it  is  notorious  that  a  rejection  of  all 


NEW  BOOKS.  527 

metaphysics  is  the  most  metaphysical  of  positions"  (III.,  p.  147,  148). 
"  All  through  the  centuries  thought  has  been  observed  trailing  a  cloud  of 
speculation — and  here,  in  the  middle  of  the  nineteenth  century,  we  find 
the  same  problems  that  troubled  Plato  still  unsolved,  and  a  mind  that 
embraces  Platonism  and  Atomism  [Fechner]  repeating  again  the  lost 
formulae  that  should  exorcise  the  mystery  "  (p.  129). 

Accordingly  Mr.  Brett's  discussions  of  the  psychologists  are  rarely  other 
than  philosophical.  On  the  purely  experimental  psychology  of  recent 
years  he  touches  in  passing,  as  in  discussing  Fechner  and  Wundt, 
Ebbinghaus,  "the  Wiirzburg  School,"  but  even  in  these  it  is  the  under- 
lying questions,  the  relation  of  mind  and  body,  the  analysis  of  the  thought- 
process,  etc.,  that  interest  him,  rather  than  the  methods  and  detailed 
results.  (This  gap  is  filled,  however,  by  Klemm's  useful  history.)  The 
theory  of  Vision — colour-sense,  perception  of  form,  localisation — is  taken 
up  more  thoroughly,  from  the  interesting  account  of  Alhazen  (II. ,  59  to 
63)  onwards  to  Descartes,  Johannes  Miiller,  Helinholtz,  Lotze,  etc.  Per- 
haps Mr.  Brett's  interest  in  vision  and  its  psychology  leads  him  rather  to 
neglect  Stumpf  and  G.  E.  Miiller,  among  modern  psychologists  ;  their  im- 
portance is  greater  than  the  relative  space  he  allows  them  suggests. 

Of  the  moderns,  Lotze,  Ward,  and  Stout  are  evidently  recognised  as 
satisfying  Mr.  Brett's  own  psychological  ideals ;  Lotze,  because  with  him 
"  the  high  tide  of  intellectualism  has  already  turned  ;  feeling  is  given  a 
prominent  and  significant  place  in  the  system,"  and  the  value  alike  of 
physiology  to  psychology  and  of  psychology  to  physiology  is  recognised  ; 
Dr.  Ward  for  his  theory  of  psychic  activity — "Ward  broke  new  ground 
on  one  fundamental  point — the  idea  that  life  and  growth  belong  to  the 
mind  as  truly  as  they  belong  to  the  body.  The  total  impression  is  that 
of  a  process  which  must  be  described  piecemeal,  but  takes  place  always 
as  a  whole ;  it  is  an  impression  of  organic  unity,  an  impression  of  vital 
impulse  ever  extending  its  unity  over  a  greater  variety  and  complexity  of 
action.  To  grasp  this  idea  is  more  important  than  disputing  details,  for 
out  of  the  idea  comes  inspiration  "  (III.,  p.  239). 

The  whole  work  is  remarkably  fresh,  vivid  and  attractively  written  ; 
psychologists  will  be  grateful  that  a  work  of  this  kind  has  at  last  been 
done,  and  done  by  one  who  has  the  scholarship,  science,  and  philosophical 
training  that  are  requisite  for  the  task. 

At  the  end  of  each  volume  there  are  useful  references  to  the  literature. 
One  or  two  errors  have  slipped  into  the  text ;  on  p.  279  (Vol.  II.),  "Gray  " 
should  be  Gay — the  clergyman  who  put  Hartley  upon  the  way  of  Associa- 
tion. On  p.  278,  text  and  note  seem  to  have  some  confusion  with  regard 
to  Hartley's  work.  The  German  translation  and  notes  seem  to  have 
been  first  published  in  1772-1773  ;  these  German  notes  to  have  been  trans- 
lated and  added  to  the  second  edition  of  Hartley's  complete  work,  1791 ; 
the  fourth  edition,  1801,  had  Priestley's  additions  instead  of  the  German 
ones,,  and  the  fifth  edition,  1810,  had  no  additions.  .» 

J.  L.  M. 

Received  also  : — 

Aristotle,  the  Works  of,  translated  into  English,  De  Caelo,  by  J.  L.  Stocks, 
and  De  Generatione  et  Corruptions,  by  H.  H.  Joachim,  Oxford, 
Clarendon  Press,  1922,  pp.  vi,  268a-313b ;  vi,  314a-338b. 

C.  Flammarion,  At  the  Moment  of  Death,  trans,  by  Latrobe  Carroll,  Lon- 
don, T.  Fisher  Uiiwin,  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  371. 

K.  Stephen,  The  Misuse  of  Mind :  A  Study  of  Bergson's  Attack  on  Intel- 
lectualism, London,  Kegan  Paul,  Trench,  Trubner  &    Co.  Ltd 
1922,  pp.  107. 


528  NEW   BOOKS. 

Aristotle  on  Coming-to-be  and  Passing -away,  A  Revised  Text,  with  Intro- 
duction and  Commentary,  by  H.  H.  Joachim,  Oxford,  Clarendon 
Press,  1922,  pp.  xxxviii,  303. 

H.  Wildon  Carr,  A  Theory  of  Monads,  London,  Macmillan  &  Co.  Ltd.,. 
1922,  pp.  viii,  351. 

G.  E.  Moore,  Philosophical  Studies,  London,  Kegan  Paul,  Trench,  Trub- 
ner  &  Co.  Ltd  ,  1922,  pp.  viii,  342. 

H.  Hoffding,  Der  Relationsbegriff,  Leipzig,  O.  R.  Reisland,  1922,  pp.  99. 

E.  L.  Heermance,  Chaos  or  Cosmos  ?  New  York,  E.  P.  Dutton  &  Co.,, 
1922,  pp.  xxi,  358. 

E.  Galli,  Nel  Regno  del  Conoscere  e  del  Ragionare,  Milan,  Fratelli  Bocca, 
1919,  pp.  300. 

E.  Galli,  Alle  Soglie  della  Metafisica,  Milan,  Societa  Edit.  "  Unitas," 
1922,  pp.  223. 

G.  Shann,  The  Evolution  of  Knowledge,  London,  Longmans,  Green  &  Co.  r 
1922,  pp.  vi,  100. 

D.  Nys,  La  Notion  d'Espace,  Brussels,  R.  Sand,  1922,  pp.  446. 

L.  Rougier,  Philosophy  and  the  New  Physics,  translated  by  M.  Masius, 
London,  G.  Routledge  &  Sons,  Ltd.,  pp.  xv,  159. 

E.  Esclangon,  Les  Preuves  Astronomiques  de  la  Relativite,  Paris,  Gauthier- 

Villars  &  Cie.,  1922,  pp.  27. 
S.  K.  Maitra,  The  Neo-romantic  Movement  in  Contemporary  Philosophy, 

Calcutta,  The  Book  Co.,  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  268. 
J.   Endara,  Jose  Ingenieros   y  el   Porvenir  de  la  Filosofia,  2nd  edition, 

Buenos  Aires,  Agencia  General  de  Libreria,  pp.  100. 
H.  Drie.-ch,  Geschichte  des  Vitalismus,  2nd  enlarged  edition  of  Part  I.  of 

"Der  Vitalismus  als  Geschichte  und  als  Lehre,"  Leipzig,  J.   A. 

Barth,  1922,  pp.  x,  213. 
M.  Granet,  La  Religion  des  Chinois,  Paris,  Gauthier-Villars  &  Cie,  1922, 

pp.  xiii,  202. 
Chronicon  Spinozanum,  Tomus  L,  The  Hague,  Societas  Spinozana,  1921, 

pp.  xxiv,,  326. 
M.  G.  Peucesco,  Le  Mecanisme  du  Courant  de  la  Conscience,  Paris,  K 

Alcan,  1922,  pp.  190. 
C.  G.  Lange  and  W.  James,  The  Emotions  (Psychology  Classics,  Vol.  I.), 

Baltimore,  Williams  &  Wilkins  Co.,  1922,  pp.  135. 
E.  Rignano,  Come  Funziona  la  nostra  Intelligenza,  Bologna,  N.  Zanichelli, 

1922,  pp.  46. 
M.  Hamblin  Smith,  The  Psychology  of  the  Criminal,  London,  Methuen  & 

Co.  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  vi,  182. 
H.   H.  Goddard,  Juvenile  Delinquency,  London,  Kegan  Paul,  Trench, 

Trubner  &  Co.  Ltd.,  pp.  v,  120. 
C.  W.  Beers,  A  Mind  that  Found  Itself :  an  Autobiography,  5th  Edition, 

Longmans,  Green  &  Co.,  1921,  pp.  368. 
S.  Paton,  Human  Behavior,  London,  G.  Allen  &  Unwin,  Ltd.,  pp.  v,  465, 

E.  Underbill,   The  Life  of  the  Spirit  and  the  Life  of  To-day,  London, 

Methuen  &  Co.  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  xii.  241. 

N.  C.  Mukerji,  The  Ethical  and  Religious  Philosophy  of  Idealism,  Alla- 
habad, North  India  Christian  Tract  Society,  1922,  pp.  xviii,  149. 

G.  Heymans,  Einfuhrung  in  die  Ethik  auf  Grundlage  der  Erfahrung,  2nd 
edition,  Leipzig,  J.  A.  Barth,  1922,  pp.  v.,  323. 

Smithsonian  Institution,  Annual  Report  for  1919,  Washington,  Govern- 
ment Printing  Office.  1921,  pp.  xii,  557. 

Carnegie  Endowment  for  International  Peace,  Year  Book,  1920,  Washing- 
ton, 2  Jackson  Place,  pp.  xiv,  244. 

F.  Boas,  Ethnology  of  the  Kwakiutl  (35th  Annual  Report  of  the  Bureau 

of  American  Ethnology,  1913-14,  Part  II.),  Washington,  Govern- 
ment Printing  Office,  1921,  pp.  viii,  795-1481. 


NEW  BOOKS.  529 

F.  La  Flesche,  The  Osage  Tribe  (36th  Annual  Report  of  the  Bureau  of 
American  Ethnology,  1914-15),  Washington,  Government  Printing 
Office,  1921,  pp.  604. 

A.  M.  Tozzer,  Excavation  of  a  Site  at  Santiago  Ahuitzotla,  D.  F.  Mexico 
(Bureau  of  American  Ethnology,  Bulletin  74),  Washington,  Govern- 
ment Printing  Office,  1921,  pp.  55,  plates  19. 

R.  Eager,  Hints  to  Probationer  Nurses  in  Mental  Hospitals,  London, 
H,  K.  Lewis  &  Co.,  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  80. 

H.  Price,  Cold  Light  on  Spiritualistic  *  *  Phenomena  "  (reprinted  from  the 
Journal  of  the  S.P.R.,  May,  1922),  London,  Kegan  Paul,  Trench, 
Trubner  &  Co.  Ltd.,  1922,  pp.  15. 


34 


VIII.— PHILOSOPHICAL  PEKIODICALS. 

THE  BRITISH  JOURNAL  OP  PSYCHOLOGY.  Vol.  xii. ,  Part  2.  October, 
1921.  W.  H.  R.  Rivers.  'Affect  in  the  Dream.'  [The  author  accepts 
the  view  that  dreams  are  the  attempt  to  solve  in  sleep  the  conflicts  of 
waking  life  and  points  out  that,  since  in  sleep  only  the  earlier  levels  of 
mental  processes  are  functioning,  the  solution  of  the  conflict  must  take  on 
an  infantile  aspect.  Transformation  in  dreams  is  thus  a  form  of  regression 
and  is  not  due  to  the  work  of  a  " censor".  Its  effect  is  to  lessen  the 
affective  aspect  of  the  conflict.  When  there  is  no  transformation  there  is 
affect,  pleasant  or  unpleasant  according  to  whether  the  strongest  wishes 
of  the  dreamer  are  fulfilled  or  not.  The  intensity  of  affect  is  itself  a  mark 
of  the  infantile  nature  of  the  dream.]  P.  B.  Baflard.  '  The  Limit  of  the 
growth  of  Intelligence.'  [Describes  the  application  of  a  series  of  "ab- 
surdity "  tests  among  pupils  and  students  from  eleven  to  twenty- two  years 
of  age  or  more.  No  greater  superiority  in  these  tests  is  shown  by  pupils 
over  sixteen  years,  from  which  it  is  inferred  that  "intelligence"  ceases 
to  grow  about  the  age  of  sixteen  or  grows  at  only  a  very  slow  rate.] 
B.  Muscio.  'Feeling-tone  in  Industry.'  [Reaffirms  the  importance  of 
feelings  of  fatigue  as  determinants  of  output,  though  they  may  not  be 
correlated  very  highly  with  output  in  experimental  work  done  under 
highest  pressure.  Reports  as  to  fatigue  at  different  times  of  the  day  by 
twenty  individual  students  and  fifteen  typists  show  rough  correspondence 
between  the  degree  of  freshness  and  normal  industrial  output.  "  It  is 
strongly  suggested  that  the  deterioration  of  output  towards  the  end  of  a 
spell  of  work  is  a  direct  response  to  the  painful  feeling-tone  of  these 
'  feelings'  of  fatigue. "  These  feelings  may  thus  play  a  far  greater  part  in 
normal  work  than  current  fatigue  investigation,  engrossed  with  physio- 
logical problems,  recognises.  And  it  is  suggested  that  "feelings" 
generally — and  not  merely  '  *  fatigue  "  feelings — "  should  be  accorded  more 
notice  in  connexion  with  various  sides  of  industrial  life  than  they  at 
present  receive".]  T.  H.  Pear.  'The  Intellectual  Respectability  of 
Muscular  Skill. '  [Discusses  the  value  of  kinsesthesis,  its  loose  connexion 
with  language,  and  the  marked  degree  of  individual  variations  in  respect 
to  kinaesthetic  imagery.  He  enquires  into  the  possibility  of  a  "language 
of  kinsesthesis"  emphasising  what  its  value  would  be  in  motion  study. 
Other  questions  discussed  are  the  '  intolerance '  of  persons  with  pre- 
dominant kinds  of  imagery,  the  utility  of  visual  imagery  in  learning 
muscular  co-ordinations,  and  the  improvement  of  the  social  and  intellectual 
status  of  kinsesthetic  knowledge.]  Other  articles  in  this  number  are  as 
follows:  H.  Hartridge.  'A  Vindication  of  the  Resonance  Theory  of 
Audition,'  H.  A.  Q.  Sillitoe.  'A  Portable  Choice  Reaction  Time 
Apparatus '  (with  diagram).  Charles  Fox.  f  A  New  Method  of  Marking 
Group  Tests.'  Charles  Fox.  Critical  notice  of  J.  C.  Maxwell  Garnett's 
'  Education  and  World  Citizenship :  an  essay  towards  a  science  of  Educa- 
tion'. 


PHILOSOPHICAL  PERIODICALS.  531 

LOGOS.     Anno  iv.,  Fasc.  4.     October-December,  1921.     C.  Schuwer. 

La  philosophie  et  les  systemes.  [The  author's  main  thesis  is  that  the  true 
phitosophi:i  perennis  is  the  gradual  creation  of  time  which  integrates  the 
thought  contained  in  the  various  "systems  "  of  individual  thinkers  into  a 
permanent  and  coherent  whole.]  A.  Chiappelli.  Dinamica  spirituale. 
[A  good  essay  on  the  necessity  of  a  genuine  Theism  as  the  only  way  of 
reconciling  the  unity  of  aim  and  tendency  in  the  known  world  with  the 
plurality  of  finite  subjects.  But  why  does  the  author  think  it  necessary 
to  deny  the  reality  of  the  distinction  between  good  and  evil  ?  To  argue 
that  the  tendency  of  the  world  is  to  the  elimination  of  evil  one  need  not 
deny  that^  as  things  are,  evil  is  very  real  and  that  it  is  just  because  it  is 
so  real  that  it  needs  to  be  overcome  and  cannot  be  simply  ignored.  But 
it  is  gratifying  to  see  that  the  fancy  of  a  "finite  God"  is  absolutely 
rejected.]  E.  di  Carlo.  Teoria  filosofica  del  diritto.  [Why  are  not  all 
"events,"  but  only  human  actions,  the  "  field  "  of  law  ?  Because  human 
actions  are  not  mere  events,  but  acts,  "  in  immediate  correlation  with  the 
volitional  activity  of  a  human  subject".  What,  then,  are  the  specific 
characters  of  an  act  ?  The  all-important  point  is  that  "  imputable  acts  " 
issue  from  deliberation.  Hence  Del  Vecchio's  definition,  "an  act  is  the 
mode  of  being  of  a  subject  in  so  far  as  it  has  its  principium  in  the  sub- 
ject," is  too  wide.  It  would  include  mere  physical  reflexes  and  sense- 
reflexes.  Mere  thoughts,  again,  cannot  come  under  the  cognizance  of 
the  law.]  N.  Abbagnano.  II  realismo  critico  in  America.  [A  brief  ex- 
position of  the  main  thesis  of  the  "six  realists,"  mainly  directed  to  the 
point  that,  on  their  theory,  the  actual  existence,  the  "that"  of  the  ob- 
ject known,  is  asserted  on  the  strength  of  an  extra-logical  instinct.] 
W.  Riley.  American  Realism  and  Its  Critics,  i.  [A  severe  criticism  of 
Messrs.  Sellars  and  Spaulding,  which  suggests  that  not  only  do  they  not 
know  their  own  meaning,  but  that  their  doctrines  really  have  no  coherent 
meaning.  I  could  wish  there  had  been  a  marked  protest  against  the 
ignorant  attempt  to  shelter  what  seems  to  be  only  a  "neutral  monism," 
obscurely  expressed,  under  the  name  of  Plato,  an  authority  with  whom 
the  "  neo-realists  "  in  question  do  not  seem  to  have  very  close  acquaint- 
ance. And  I  do  not  see  that  the  "traditional  account  of  consciousness," 
whatever  it  is,  is  "  done  for  "  by  simply  calling  consciousness  an  "  aware- 
ness" or  a  "dimension".]  A.  Aliotta.  II  razionalismo  e  ie  verite  mate- 
matiche.  [A.  maintains  that  the  method  of  pure  mathematics  is 
throughout  radically  "experimental".  It  is  all  a  matter  of  making 
hypotheses  and  verifying  them.  The  "  a-priorists,"  from  Plato  to 
Russell,  are  regarded  as  refuted  by  the  considerations  (a)  that  different 
geometries  are  equally  legitimate,  (6)  that  the  choice  of  indefinables  and 
indemonstrables  is,  in  part,  arbitrary,  (c)  that  the  demonstrations  of 
geometry  only  prove  logical  implications.  But  when  all  this  is  admitted, 
is  "Platonism"  really  disposed  of?  As  the  Phaedo  shows,  Plato's 
doctrine  was  not  really  what  A.  calls  it,  a  "crude  intuitionalism". 
Granted  that  all  the  geometer  proves  is  that  his  postulates  logically 
imply  his  conclusions,  are  the  laws  of  logical  implication  themselves 
arrived  at  by  a  previous  experimentation?  The  unresolved  difficulty, 
to  my  mind,  is  that  in  genuine  experimentation  you  have  always  some- 
thing by  comparison  with  which  you  may  "  verify  "  your  hypothesis  ;  in 
pure  mathematics,  there  seems  to  be  nothing  outside  the  body  of  deduc- 
tions from  your  postulates  which  could  serve  to  "verify  "  the  postulates. 
The  body  of  deduced  consequences  has  to  be  at  once  the  inference  from 
the  hypothesis  and  the  evidence  by  comparison  with  which  the  hypothesis 
is  verified.]  Q.  Delia  Valle.  L'apriorita  dell'  intuizione  e  I'universalita 
dei  Valori.  ["  Values  "  arise  from  an  intuition  which  consists  in  the  ap- 
plication a  priori  of  a  specific  category  of  value  to  a  mental  state.  Value 


532  PHILOSOPHICAL   PEEIODICALS. 

— the  category — is  always  one  and  identical ;  differences  of  quality  between 
values  are  due  to  differences  of  the  extent  to  which  the  category  is  applied. 
Knowledge  is  a  special  case  of  valuation.]  Reviews. 

RIVISTA  DI  FILOSOFIA  NEO-ScoLASTiCA.  Anno  xiii.,  Fasc.  v.  Sep- 
tember-October, 1921.  Editorial.  [Explains  the  inauguration  at  Milan 
on  the  preceding  7th  December  of  the  Catholic  University  of  the  Sacred 
Heart,  of  which  this  Review  now  becomes  the  official  organ,  and  the  or- 
ganisation in  particular  of  the  department  of  Philosophy.  Tne  projected 
course  seems  a  very  sound  and  thorough  one  ;  the  present  writer  wishes 
the  new  University  much  success  in  its  work.]  Q.  Cattaneo.  Roberto 
Ardigo  nei  ricordi  d'uno  del  suoi  primi  discepoli  all'  Universitd,  di  Padova. 
[Reminiscences  of  the  famous  ex-priest  and  Positivist  by  an  early  pupil, 
a  student  at  Padua  when  Ardigo  was  appointed  there  in  1881.]  Q.  Sestili. 
La  Filosofia  di  S.  Bonaventura.  [A  careful  study  of  S.  Bona Ventura's 
most  characteristic  doctrines  of  (a)  the  aim  of  philosophy,  (b)  created 
things,  (c)  knowledge.  Well-documented ;  I  confess  the  defence  of  the 
"  ontological  argument "  seems  to  me  to  evade  the  real  difficulty.  The 
author  seems  to  me  to  establish  only  the  hypothetical  proposition,  "  if 
there  is  a  God,  He  exists,"  or  "if  God  is  known,  He  is  known  as  exist- 
ing ".  The  persistent  objector  would  probably  say,  like  Hobbes,  that  God 
may  be  imagined  or  thought  of,  but  is  not  known  at  all.]  C.  Baeumker. 
Pietro  d'Ibernia.  [Continuation  of  the  article  begun  in  Fasc.  ii.  Peter's 
disputation  before  Manfred  shows  no  Augustinian  influence.  It  is  wholly 
a  product  of  the  Aristotelian  movement ;  the  author's  connexions  are  with 
medicine  and  natural  science,  not  with  theology,  and  his  guide  to  Aris- 
totle's meaning  is  not  Avicenna  but  the  less  Nee-Platonic  Averroes.  His 
Aristotelianism  may  probably  have  been  a  formative  influence  in  the 
thought  of  his  disciple  St.  Thomas.  The  Latin  text  of  the  disputation  is 
given.]  Reviews.  Anno  xiii.,  Fasc.  vi.  November-December,  1921. 
E.  Ciafardini.  L'immortalita  delV  anima  in  Cicerone.  [A  discussion 
of  Cicero's  first  Tusculan,  marked  by  sympathetic  understanding  of 
Cicero's  personality.  But  the  Platonic  proof  that  the  "  motion  which 
moves  itself  "  is  everlasting  is  much  more  fully  expounded  in  the  Laws, 
to  which  no  reference  is  made,  than  in  the  Phaedrus,  and  a  study  of 
Prof.  Burnet's  edition  of  the  Phaedo  might  lead  Mr.  Ciafardini  to  re- 
consider his  remarks  about  the  historical  character  of  the  picture  of 
Socrates  in  the  Phaedo.]  P.  Rotta.  Del  Platonismo  in  Aristoteie.  [Con- 
cluded from  the  issue  for  January-February,  1921.  The  author  rightly 
dwells  on  the  point  that  the  opposition  between  Platonism  and  Aris- 
totelianism is  far  from  being  so  sharp  as  the  tone  of  Aristotle's  own 
criticisms  would  suggest.  His  view  is  that  Aristotle  habitually  forgets 
that  Plato's  doctrine  is  primarily  epistemological  whereas  his  own  is 
cosmological.  I  am  not  sure  that  this  distinction  is  really  valid.  To 
understand  Plato's  thought  we  should  surely  start  rather  from  the  notices 
of  his  teaching  furnished  by  Aristotle  himself  and  other  immediate  pupils, 
and  from  works  where  Plato  is  not  hampered  by  the  necessity  of  keeping 
up  the  dramatic  fiction  that  we  are  listening  to  a  conversation  held  in  the 
fifth  century,  that  is  from  the  Laws,  the  Epinomis,  the  Epistles,  than  from 
the  Philebus  and  Timceus,  where  we  are  dealing  with  the  ideas  of  fifth- 
century  Pythagoreanism.  The  Philebus  may  serve  as  an  instantia  crucis. 
We  know  from  Aristotle  that  the  Pythagorean  antithesis  of  Infinite  and 
Limit  was  not  accepted,  in  that  form,  by  Plato,  and  that  this  was  one  of  the 
two  points  which,  according  to  Aristotle,  made  the  difference  between  the 
two  philosophies.  Yet  all  through  the  Philebus  Plato  works,  obviously 
from  a  desire  for  dramatic  verisimilitude,  with  the  Pythagorean  categories. 
Robin,  to  my  mind,  is  obviously  beginning  at  the  right  end  in  attempting 


PHILOSOPHICAL   PEEIODICALS.  533 

to  get  at  Plato's  thought  by  asking  how  it  was  understood  by  such  men  as 
Aristotle,  Xenocrates,  Speusippus.  Now  the  Laws  shows  that,  so  far 
from  the  conception  of  God  playing  a  subordinate  part  in  Plato's  thought, 
it  was  this  concept,  and  the  use  of  it  to  solve  the  cosrnological  problem, 
which  was  central  in  Platonism.  If  I  might  make  a  suggestion,  I  could 
wish  that  a  neo-scholastic  would  attempt  to  discuss  the  question  whether 
the  real  perennis  pkilosophia  is  not  just  the  Platonism  in  Aristotle,  and 
whether  everything  in  Aristotle  which  is  not  really  in  Plato  is  more  than 
an  obstinate  survival  of  "  naturalistic  "  prejudices  due  to  early  education 
in  Ionian  cosmology  and  biology.  Mr.  Rotta  has  naturally  a  great  deal 
to  say  of  the  so-called  vovs  TTOITJTIKOS.  Is  not  the  appearance  of  this 
disturbing  "  supernatural  "  entity  at  the  end  of  an  otherwise  naturalistic 
work  on  psychology  just  an  example  of  Platonism  imperfectly  amalga- 
mated with  Ionian  naturalism  ?]  L.  Stefanini.  Morte  e  vita  nel  pensiero 
di  G.  V.  Gravina.  [Concluded  from  an.  xii.,  fasc.  vi.]  Notes  and  discus- 
sions. Lo  stato  attuale  della  filosofia  tedesca.  [A  good  general  survey. 
But  why  cannot  the  champions  of  the  philotophia  perennis  speak  of  Kant 
fairly  and  dispassionately  ?  We  need  be  no  Kantian  to  be  alive  to  the 
facts  that  Kant  was  a  considerable  thinker  and  that  the  version  of  his 
thought  given  by  the  "  idealist "  neo-Kantians  is  a  travesty.  Why  must 
Kant  be  the  scape-goat  for  the  sins  of  men  whom  he  would  have  been 
the  first  to  disown?  And — it  is  a  small  matter  but  significant— Kant 
never  wrote  a  work  on  Religion  within  the  limits  of  Pure  Reason.  What 
he  did  write  of  was  Religion  within  the  limits  of  Mere  Reason,  a  very 
different  matter.]  Reviews. 

RIVISTA  DI  FILOSOFIA.  Anno  xiii.,  No.  3.  July-September,  1921. 
P.  Carabellese.  Che  cosa  e  la  Filosofia  ?  [The  discussion  starts  with  the 
views  of  Gentile  and  Croce,  the  latter  of  whom  really  abolishes  philosophy 
as  such  by  making  it  identical  with  its  own  history.  The  writer's  own 
view  is  that  philosophy  is  wrongly  described  as  "  knowledge  "  ;  it  should 
be  more  precisely  called  "theory".  It  is  theory  with  the  universal  for 
its  object,  not  the  so-called  "concrete"  universal,  but  the  abstract  uni- 
versals  of  which  all  concretes  are  the  synthesis.  Such  universals  are  the 
limits  of  the  concrete  and  are  never  absolutely  reached.  Philosophy, 
similarly,  is  always  in  the  making,  never  made.]  L.  Vivante.  DelV  in- 
telligenza  nell'  espressione.  [The  distinctive  characteristic  of  poetical  utter- 
ance is  that  the  "  matter,"  words,  rhythm,  rhyme  is  not  a  mere  external 
vehicle  for  an  already  formed  thought ;  it  suggests  and  provokes  the  thought. 
Of  course  this  is  true  in  a  lesser  degree  of  good  prose.]  G.  Semprini. 
Sul  misticismo.  [Mysticism  not  "  pathological  "  nor  yet  identical  with 
religion.]  Reviews,  etc.  Anno  xiii.,  No.  4,  October-December,  1921.  C. 
Quastella.  II  concetto  fenomenistico  dell'  identita  del  me  e  delV  incos- 
ciente.  [An  extract  from  the  author's  Ragione  del  fenomenismo."]  G.  Mon- 
tesano.  Psicologia  del  riso  e  del  comico.  [Numerous  theories  of  the 
"laughable  "  or  "  comic,"  from  Plato  to  Freud,  are  reviewed,  and  all  found 
inadequate.  The  author's  own  view  is  that  laughter,  a  sudden  explosion  by 
which  energy  is  diverted  into  new  muscular  channels,  is  valuable  as  giving 
relief  from  muscular  fatigue.  The  source  of  the  sudden  explosion  can  be 
explained  psychologically  by  starting  with  the  simple  case  where  we  amuse 
ourfeelves  by  "  playing  a  trick  "  on  some  one.  What  causes  the  explosion 
and  gives  the  relief,  and  so  causes  the  laughter  when  we  "drop  the  mask,"  is 
the  contrast  between  the  attitude  we  pretend  to  be  keeping  up  and  the  very 
different  one  we  are  shortly  to  assume.  This  gives  us  a  clue  to  the  char- 
acter of  the  "  comic  "  situation  in  general.  Here  the  whole  situation  may 
be  a  feigned  one,  but  the  point  of  it  lies  in  sympathetic  appreciation  of  the 
relief  which  comes  from  a  momentary  throwing  off  of  the  inhibitions 


534  PHILOSOPHICAL   PERIODICALS. 

conventionally  imposed  on  our  social  behaviour  and  of  the  fatigue  of  keeping 
them  up.  The  theory  is  cleverly  worked  out  with  a  good  deal  of  detail^ 
but  one  may  perhaps  suspect  that  it  is  a  little  too  simple.  I  would  sug- 
gest that  the  discussion  of  "laughter"  should  be  kept  carefully  apart  from 
that  of  the  "comic  ".  There  is  much  laughter  which  is  not  provoked  by 
the  "  comic".  Laughter  may  be  an  expression  of  pain,  of  anger,  of  sheer 
affection.  Nor  is  this  remarkable  when  we  remember  the  diffused  char- 
acter of  the  bodily  expressions  of  emotion.  And  is  it  clear  that  the  pro- 
posed explanation  of  the  u comic"  itself  explains,  e.g.,  why  some  of  us 
find  Henry  James's  Ambassadors  a  masterpiece  of  the  comic  art  ?  But  the 
article  at  any  rate  deserves  careful  study.]  E.  di  Carlo.  Tre  lettere  in- 
edite  del  P.  Luigi  Taparelli  D'Azeglio  a  V.  Gioberti.  Reviews,  etc. 

REVUE  NEO-SCOLASTIQUE  DE  PHILOSOPHIE.  xxive  Anne"e.  No.  93. 
February,  1922.  C.  H.  Grandgent.  Dante,  Scholar  and  Philosopher. 
[A  study  by  the  Professor  of  Romance  literature  at  Harvard].  D.  Lottin. 
Les  elements  de  la  moralite  des  actes  dans  les  ecoles  avant  Saint  Thomas. 
[On  the  answers  given  by  earlier  schoolmen  to  the  question  whether  the 
morality  of  an  act  depends  solely  on  the  agent's  intention.  A  summary  of 
the  views  of  Abelard,  Hugh  of  St.  Victor,  Peter  Lombard,  Albert  the 
Great,  Alexander  of  Hales.]  D.  Nys.  L'espace  reel  ou  I'univers  actuel 
est-il  infini  ?  [The  arguments  for  and  against  the  possibility  of  the  actual 
infinite  are  alike  inconclusive.  The  attempts  of  modern  times  to  prove 
either  the  finitude  or  the  infinitude  of  the  universe  by  appeal  to  physics 
or  astronomy  (Olbers,  Arrhenius,  Wundt  and  others)  are  equally  inconclu- 
sive. The  author's  own  view  is  that  from  consideration  of  what  would 
happen  if  the  Creator  gave  a  body  "  at  the  boundary  "  of  the  universe  an 
initial  velocity  and  at  the  same  time  deprived  it  of  gravity  we  are  driven 
to  accept  either  a  "  real  infinite  space,  "-i.e.,  I  suppose,  an  infinite  plurality 
of  "  stellar  systems,"  or  the  infinite  void.]  R.  Kremer.  La  Connaissance 
Historique,  son  objet  et  sa  nature.  [An  excellent  and  careful  essay  on  the 
impossibility  of  regarding  history  as  a  science  in  the  same  sense  as  either 
the  "exact  "or  the  "  positive"  sciences.  The  root  of  the  difficulty  is 
that  history  is  concerned  with  the  concrete  past,  the  devenir  de 
Vhumanite.]  Reviews,  etc. 


JOURNAL  OF  PHILOSOPHY,  xix.  (1922),  6.  Q.  A.  Tawney  and  E.  L. 
Talbot.  '  Democracy  and  Morals. '  [A  defence  of  Dewey's  social  philosophy 
against  the  charge  of  '  radicalism  '  which  is  so  deadly  just  now  to  American 
professors.]  J.  E.  Turner.  'Dr.  A.  N.  Whitehead's  Scientific  Realism.' 
[Does  not  "see  anything  which  prevents  realism  from  taking  its  place 
within  a  system  of  absolute  idealism  fuller  and  deeper  than  any  yet 
conceived  "  !]  Q.  H.  Mead.  *  A  Behavioristic  Account  of  the  Significant 
Symbol.'  ["  Significance  belongs  to  things  in  their  relation  and  to 
individuals.  It  does  not  lie  in  mental  processes  which  are  enclosed 
within  individuals."]  xix.,  7.  S.  P.  Lamprecht.  'The  Metaphysical 
Status  of  Sensations.'  [Seeks  salvation  in  "Plato's  contention  that  in 
vision  the  eye  becomes  a  seeing  eye,  and  the  object  becomes  a  white 
object".]  J.  L.  Mursell.  'Truth  as  Correspondence:  A  Redefinition. ' 
[To  "  avoid  the  well-known  dialectical  difficulties  of  the  theory  of  error  ". 
"  Little  is  known  as  yet  of  the  means  by  which  the  nervous  system  makes 
selections  from  and  performs  integrations  upon  the  vast  number  of  stimuli 
which  come  in  all  the  time.  But  psychology  and  neurology  are  decidedly 
justified  in  assuming  that  this  enormously  complex  mechanism  performs 
its  task  somehow.  .  .  ."  Thus  "every  judgment  is  uniquely  related  to 
its  object  by  virtue  of  the  fact  that  it  is  a  response  to  which  the  object  in 
question  has  been  or  is  the  stimulus"  and  it  is  "true  when  it  is  the 


PHILOSOPHICAL  PERIODICALS.  535 

response  of  a  normal  organism  to  a  given  stimulus".]  T.  de  Laguna. 
'  The  Complex  Dilemma  ;  A  Rejoinder.'  [To  A.  P.  Brogan,  xviii.,  21.] 
xix.,  8.  R.  Demos.  'Romanticism  vs.  the  Worship  of  Facts.'  [The 
romantic  seeks  to  escape  from  the  actual  into  the  real,  and  "  the  actual 
world  is  only  one  of  the  infinite  possible  worlds" — in  which  "existence 
is  an  evil  and  creation  the  original  sin  ".]  H.  A.  Wadman.  '  Relativity, 
Old  and  New.'  [Criticises  Turner  in  xix.,  6.]  W.  R.  Wells.  'An 
Historical  Anticipation  of  John  Fiske's  Theory  regarding  the  Value  of 
Infancy.'  [By  'V.  F.'  in  The  Friend's  Annual  for  1834.]  H.  H.  Park- 
hurst  reports  on  the  21st  Annual  Meeting  of  the  American  Philosophical 
Association,  xix.  9.  Q.  P.  Conger.  '  The  Implicit  Duality  of  Think- 
ing.' [Deduces  it  from  the  selectiveness  of  perception  and  relation  of 
every  object  to  its  background,  and  declares  it  "  a  metaphysical  principle 
of  prime  importance".]  A.  A.  Merrill.  '  The  t  of  Physics.'  ["Is  the 
fourth  dimension  of  experience  lived  as  real  time,  but  treated  mathemati- 
cally as  if  it  were  space,"  as  if  it  could  =  0.  But  "  we  live  in  real  time 
and  not  in  the  t  of  physics  ".]  W.  T.  Bush  reports  on  the  Paris  Philo- 
sophical Congress  at  Christmas,  1921. 

INTERNATIONAL  JOURNAL  OF  ETHICS,  xxxii.,2.  January,  1922.  Arthur 
Henderson.  'The  Character  and  Policy  of  the  British  Labour  Party. ' 
[Claims  that  basis  of  the  party  is  intellectual,  not  economic,  though  its 
members  are  naturally  largely  also  members  of  Trades  Unions  ;  states 
that  its  aim  is  to  control  government  and  that  its  policy  will  be  directed 
towards  greater  efficiency  of  industry  and  agriculture  for  public  service, 
reduction  of  unproductive  expenditure,  diminution  of  power  of  wealth  in 
politics  and  remodelling  of  diplomatic  machinery.]  Benjamin  Ives 
Oilman.  '  What  is  Liberty  ?  '  [Formulates  definition  that  liberty  ia 
acting  one's  part  in  the  resultant  will  of  all  whom  one's  purpose  concerns, 
develops  implications  that  each  should  give  the  same  weight  to  motives, 
adequately  imagined,  of  others  as  to  those  he  feels,  and  summarises  that 
liberty  is  the  sum  of  equality  and  fraternity.]  C.  J.  Cadoux.  '  The 
Individual  Factor  in  Social  Progress.'  [A  defence  of  the  view  that  though 
society  may  not  be  ready  for  the  universal  application  of  a  moral  ideal  the 
individual  accepting  it  should  act  according  to  it  and  propagate  his  views  ; 
applies  to  problems  of  divorce,  vegetarianism,  slavery  and  war.  ]  A.  B. 
Wolfe.  'Emotion,  Blame,  and  the  Scientific  Attitude  in  Relation  to 
Radical  Leadership.'  [Holds  that  attitude  based  upon  desire  for  thorough- 
going innovations  is  aroused  chiefly  by  attention  to  desires  thwarted  by 
social  maladjustments  and  leads  naturally  to  resentment,  anger  and  per- 
sonal blame,  that  these  cannot  develop  a  policy  ;  discusses  characteristics 
of  efficient  leaders  on  the  basis  of  extent  to  which  conduct  is  determined 
by  sensibility,  emotion,  sentiment,  or  impersonal  rational  intelligence,  and 
suggests  need  for  scientific  research  into  nature  of  obstructions  to  progress.] 
Benjamin  Qinzburg.  '  Hypocrisy  as  a  Pathological  Symptom. '  [Expands 
the  thesis  that  hypocrisy  is  inevitable  in  any  society  in  which  all  members 
do  not  develop  morally  at  the  same  rate  from  the  same  level.]  Alfred  H. 
Lloyd.  '  Leadership  and  Progress.'  [Assumes  that  progress  proceeds  in 
periods,  each  a  new  life  of  the  people,  summarises  conditions  precedent  to 
birth  of  such  a  new  life  and  characteristics  of  leaders  in  relation  to  organ- 
ised society,  and  maintains  that  they  partake  of  leadership  in  so  far  as  they 
are  individuals  and  interpret  life.]  Rupert  Clendon  Lodge.  '  Plato  and 
the  Moral  Standard.'  [Concludes  examination  of  Platonic  standards  ; 
maintains  that  each  of  proposed  standards  means  that  moral  conduct  is 
organised  and  directed  by  insight  into  the  genuine  structure  of  reality.} 


L' 

IX.— NOTE. 

IMAGINISM. 

REFLEXION  on  Mr.  Fawcett's  article  in  the  April  number  of  MIND,  and 
reconsideration  of  his  general  point  of  view,  assisted  by  a  good  deal  of 
correspondence  with  him,  have  convinced  me  that  some  injustice  was  done 
to  his  work  in  the  review  of  Divine  Imagining  that  I  wrote  more  than  a 
year  ago.  It  is  my  intention  to  return  to  the  subject  later ;  but,  in  the 
meantime,  a  few  words  appear  to  be  called  for . 

The  chief  significance  of  Mr.  Fawcett's  work  may  perhaps  be  best 
brought  out  by  a  reference  to  that  of  Prof.  Alexander.  In  Space,  Time 
and  Deity,  we  find  an  elaborate  account  of  almost  every  important  feature 
of  our  universe  ;  and  an  attempt  is  made  to  deduce  everything — even  the 
most  fundamental  categories — from  the  general  structure  of  Space-Time. 
It  is  a  highly  speculative  adventure,  and  can  hardly  be  expected  to  carry 
complete  conviction  to  every  mind  ;  but  to  a  considerable  extent  it  appears 
to  be  successful — certainly  at  least  not  an  obvious  failure.  But  there  is 
one  thing  of  which  he  is  confessedly  not  able  to  give  any  satisfactory 
account — viz.,  the  particular  qualities  of  things,  the  appearances  of  colour, 
sound,  smell,  etc.  Now,  I  understand  Mr.  Fawcett's  main  contention  to 
be  that  particular  qualities  can  be  best  understood  as  the  creations  of  a 
Divine  Imagining — a  view  that  recalls  the  work  of  the  Demiurge  described 
in  Plato's  Timaeus,  though  Mr.  Fawcett's  view  differs  from  that  in  several 
particulars.  Deity,  from  this  point  of  view,  instead  of  coming  at  the  end 
of  the  process  of  Creative  Evolution  (as  with  Prof.  Alexander)  has  to  be 
thought  of  as  present  and  active  at  the  beginning  ;  though  this  does  not 
preclude  the  possibility  of  a  development  in  the  Divine  towards  a  higher 
perfection — as  suggested,  for  instance,  in  the  recent  Gifford  Lectures  by 
Sir  Henry  Jones. 

If  this  view  is  adopted,  it  would  seem  that  qualities,  as  distinguished 
from  what  Prof.  Alexander  describes  as  the  *  categorial '  aspects  of  the 
Cosmos,  would  have  to  be  regarded  as  being,  in  a  sense,  arbitrary — as 
contrasted,  at  least,  with  the  strict  avaynrj  that  is  found  in  the  categorial 
framework.  It  is  in  this  sense  that  I  understand  Mr.  Fawcett  to  speak 
of  Chance  ;  just  as  Hegel  appeared  to  recognise  an  element  of  *  con- 
tingency '  in  the  created  universe.  A  view  of  this  kind  seems  to  me 
perfectly  intelligible,  though  the  particular  expression  of  it  may  be  open 
to  question.  Indeed,  it  seems  to  me  the  most  intelligible  account  of  the 
world-process  that  has  ever,  so  far  as  I  am  aware,  been  put  forward. 
Hence  I  now  regard  Mr.  Fawcett's  work  as  considerably  more  important 
than  I  at  first  perceived.  It  seems  at  least,  if  nothing  else,  to  be  the 
necessary  supplement  to  such  an  account  as  that  of  Prof.  Alexander. 

It  may  be  noted  that  the  theory,  thus  interpreted,  appears  to  involve 
that  there  is  a  real  beginning  of  the  time  process,  though  not  necessarily 
any  end.  There  seems  to  be  no  insuperable  difficulty  in  accepting  this 
view,  though  it  calls  for  a  good  deal  of  discussion.  It  does  not  preclude 
the  possibility  of  a  return  of  the  time  process  upon  itself,  such  as  Mr. 
Fawcett  appears  to  maintain. 

I  still  find  many  things  in  Mr.  Fawcett's  book  that  seem  highly  specula- 
tive ;  and  I  am  not  quite  clear  as  to  his  grounds  for  affirming  some  of  them  ; 
but  I  know  of  no  definite  grounds  for  denying  most  of  them.  His  idea  of 
creation  out  of  nothing" seems  to  call  for  more  explanation.  But,  so  far  as 
I  understand  his  main  positions,  they  seem  at  least  plausible  and  enlighten- 
ing. The  acceptance  of  them  would  involve  some  modifications  in  opinions 
that  I  have  previously  ventured  to  suggest,  but  not  so  much  change  as 
might  at  first  appear  necessary.  Of  this,  however,  more  hereafter. 

J.  S.  MACKENZIE. 


B  Mind 

1 

M65 

n.s.v.31 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 


UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO 
LIBRARY