Skip to main content

Full text of "Modern Thomistic philosophy: an explanation for students"

See other formats


UNIVERSITY 
OF  FLORIDA 
LIBRARY 


THE  GIFT  OF 

Carl  T.   Hoffman 

COLLEGE  LIBRARY 


MODERN 
THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 


Digitized  by  the  Internet  Archive 

in  2011  with  funding  from 

Lyrasis  Members  and  Sloan  Foundation 


http://www.archive.org/details/modernthomisticp01phil 


MODERN 
THOMISTIC    PHILOSOPHY 

AN   EXPLANATION   FOR   STUDENTS 


BY 

R.   P.   PHILLIPS,  D.D.,  M.A., 

Professor  of  Philosophy,  S.  John's  Seminary,  Wonersb 


IN   TWO   VOLUMES 

Vol.  I. 
THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  NATURE 


"  Vidit  scalam  stantem  super  terram 
et  cacumen  illius  tangene  caelum." 

(Gen.  c.  28,  v.  12.) 


THE  NEWMAN  BOOKSHOP 
Westminster,  Md. 


NIHIL  OBSTAT: 

Georgius  Joyce,  S.J. 
Censor  deputatus. 

IMPRIMATUR : 

S.  Canonicus  Banfi, 
Vicarius  generalis. 


SOUTHWARCI, 

1934. 


NOTE   AS   TO   THE   METHOD    OF  QUOTING 
ARISTOTLE  AND   S.   THOMAS 

The  references  to  Aristotle's  works  are,  in  accordance  with  the 
usual  practice,  numbered  according  to  the  pagination  of  the  edition 
of  Bekker  (Aristotelis  Opera.  Berlin,  1831-1870.  5  Vols.).  Since 
the  Greek  text  in  this  edition  has  a  consecutive  pagination  through- 
out, it  is  a  simple  matter  to  find  any  passage  referred  to.  Thus,  the 
first  number  given  refers  to  the  page,  the  letter  a  or  b  to  the  first  or 
second  column  of  that  page,  and  the  final  number  to  the  line  of  the 
column  in  which  the  quotation  is  to  be  found.  So,  e.g.  952a26  refers 
to  a  passage  beginning  on  the  twenty-sixth  line  of  the  first  column  of 
page  nine  hundred  and  fifty-two.  The  same  numeration  is  followed 
by  the  Oxford  translation  of  Aristotle.  (The  Works  of  Aristotle, 
translated  into  English.  Ed.  J.  A.  Smith  and  W.  D.  Ross.  11  Vols. 
Clarendon  Press,  Oxford.) 

With  regard  to  S.  Thomas,  the  method  of  reference  is  as  follows  : 
The  references  to  the  Sumrna  Theologica  give  first  the  part  of  the 
Summa  from  which  the  quotation  comes,  i.e.  I.,  the  first  part ;  I.  II., 
the  first  part  of  the  second  part ;  II.  II.,  the  second  part  of  the  second 
part ;  and  III.,  the  third  part.  Then  follows  the  number  of  the 
question,  after  which  is  given  that  of  the  article  referred  to  ;  and 
finally,  if  necessary,  the  number  of  the  objection  or  its  answer,  to 
which  reference  is  made.  Thus  :  I.  II. ,77, 5,  ad  3  would  mean  that 
the  passage  is  to  be  found  in  the  answer  to  the  third  objection  to  the 
fifth  article  of  the  seventy-seventh  question  of  the  first  part  of  the 
second  part.  The  disputed  questions  are  referred  to  by  name,  e.g. 
De  Veritate,  followed  by  the  number  of  the  question  and  article.  So, 
De  Veritate  3,2,  ad  6  refers  to  the  answer  to  the  sixth  objection  to  the 
second  article  of  the  third  question  of  that  work.  The  Summa  contra 
Gentiles  is  referred  to  by  the  number  of  the  book  and  chapter.  So, 
II. CG.  12  refers  to  the  twelfth  chapter  of  the  second  book.  In  the 
commentaries  on  Aristotle  the  number  of  the  lecture  in  which  the 
reference  occurs  is  given. 


PREFACE 

The  purpose  of  this  book  is  to  present  a  simple  explanation 
of  the  philosophy  usually  taught  to  Catholic  students.  No 
attempt  has  been  made  to  introduce  novel  doctrines,  but 
merely  to  set  out,  as  clearly  as  possible,  the  meaning  of  those 
which  are  commonly  received.  Since  such  teaching  at  the 
present  day  is  predominantly  on  the  lines  of  the  system 
originated  by  S.  Thomas  Aquinas,  it  is  this  system,  as 
developed  by  modern  Thomists,  which  it  is  the  object  of  this 
book  to  explain.  It  is  clear  that  in  a  single  work  it  would  be 
impossible  to  give  a  full  account,  and  absurd  to  try  to 
vindicate  the  truth,  of  the  various  philosophical  systems 
which  are  included  under  the  generic  name  of  Scholasticism  ; 
so  that  no  systematic  exposition  is  attempted  of  even  the 
chief  of  the  non-Thomistic  systems,  those  of  Scotus  and 
Suarez.  The  divergencies  of  their  doctrines  from  those  of 
S.  Thomas  frequently  throw  light  on  the  precise  meaning  of 
the  Thomist  contentions  ;  so  that  to  make  some  mention  of 
them  is  not  foreign  to  our  purpose.  Similar  considerations 
will  apply  to  our  treatment  of  those  other  philosophical 
systems  which  diverge  still  more  widely  from  the  Thomistic 
plan,  such  as  those  of  Spinoza  or  of  Hegel.  It  appears  to  be 
as  unreasonable  to  expect,  in  an  exposition  of  Thomism,  a 
full  account  and  refutation  of  Hegelianism,  for  example,  as 
it  would  be  to  look  for  such  an  account  of  Thomism  in  Hegel's 
Logic.  Consequently,  all  that  seems  necessary  to  be  done  in 
this  direction  is  to  notice  the  principal  divergencies  of 
modern  philosophies  from  the  Thomistic,  so  bringing  into 
higher  relief  its  positive  teaching  ;  and,  as  far  as  space  allows, 
to  meet  the  more  urgent  of  the  reasons  that  have  been 
advanced  against  its  truth. 

The  questions  which  were  most  prominent  in  S.  Thomas' 
day  are  not  so  much  to  the  fore  at  present,  while  many  of 

vii 


viii  PREFACE 

those  most  debated  ^iow,  were,  in  the  Middle  Ages,  hardly 
discussed.  The  emphasis  and  accent,  therefore,  of  a  modern 
presentation  of  Thomism  must  be  different  from  those  of  the 
expositions  of  a  John  of  S.  Thomas  or  a  Goudin  ;  though 
the  basic  principles  may  remain  the  same.  These  principles 
contain  a  view  of  the  universe ;  and  no  decision  can  be 
reached  as  to  the  truth  or  falsity  of  this  view,  by  considering 
merely  the  arguments  which  may  be  advanced  in  support  of 
particular  doctrines,  but  only  from  a  consideration  of  it  as  a 
whole.  Just  as  in  circumstantial  evidence  for  a  crime  each 
item  taken  separately  may  be  insufficient  to  make  certain  the 
identity  of  the  criminal,  yet  if  a  large  number  of  facts  of 
different  kinds  all  point  in  a  particular  direction,  the  con- 
clusion is  almost  irresistible  ;  so,  in  judging  of  the  validity  of 
a  philosophical  system,  conviction  is  reached  when  it  is  seen 
that,  from  all  sides,  our  consideration  of  the  various  elements 
of  the  universe  converge  to  establish  it.  For  the  philosopher 
is,  as  Plato  says,  a  '  synoptical  man,'  taking  a  unified  view 
of  all  knowledge.  The  world- view  of  S.  Thomas  is  essentially 
such  a  unity,  and  must,  therefore,  be  judged  as  a  whole. 
Consequently,  an  attempt  has  been  made,  in  the  following 
pages,  to  keep  the  main  principles  of  it  in  the  foreground, 
and  to  show  that  from  every  side  the  roads  of  thought  lead 
up  to  them.  To  do  this  at  all  adequately  a  discussion  of  moral 
philosophy  ought  to  be  added,  but  this  would  have  necessi- 
tated making  the  book  impracticably  long.  Fortunately, 
Fr.  Cronin  has  already  given  us  all  that  can  be  desired  in 
this  way  ;  while  an  account  of  the  Cosmological  and  Meta- 
physical sections  of  Thomistic  philosophy  is  not  available  in 
English  in  a  handy  form.  The  only  single  work  of  this  kind 
is  the  translation  of  the  Manual  of  Modern  Scholastic 
Philosophy,  compiled  by  professors  of  Louvain  University, 
but  this  includes,  in  addition  to  these  subjects,  Logic,  Ethics, 
and  the  history  of  Philosophy,  so  reducing  considerably  the 
amount  of  space  available  for  those  which  we  are  to  deal  with. 
It  is  hoped,  therefore,  that  a  somewhat  more  detailed 
explanation  in  English,  of  Natural  and  Metaphysical  philo- 
sophy, contained  in  a  single  book,  may  be  found  useful  by 
those  who  are  professedly  making  a  study  of  Scholastic 


PREFACE  ix 

philosophy  ;  and  possibly  also  by  others  who  have  not  the 
time  or  opportunity  for  reading  the  several  volumes  of  the 
Stonyhurst  series,  or  the  very  full  expositions  by  Dr.  Coffey 
of  some  of  the  subjects  here  dealt  with,  but  who,  at  the  same 
time,  would  like  to  know  something  of  this  philosophy  as  a 
whole. 


CONTENTS 

PAGE 

Preface  ..........     vii 

I.  INTRODUCTORY 

Section  I.  The  Definition  of  Philosophy  .  .  .  i 
To  be  Looked  for  in  Philosophy  as  an  Existing 
Fact — In  its  History — Thales  and  the  Ionic  School 
— The  Pythagoreans — The  Eleatics — Heracleitus — 
The  Atomists — Anaxagoras — Socrates  and  Plato — 
Aristotle — Conclusion . 

Section  II.    The  Division  of  Philosophy        ...       20 

II.  THE   PHILOSOPHY   OF  NATURE 

Part  I.     Cosmology  :     The    Philosophy    of    Inanimate 

Nature        .......       22 

Introduction. 

Chapter  I.    Mechanism      ......       25 

History  of  the  Theory — Its  Essential  Character — 
Criticism. 

Chapter  II.    Dynamism     ......       30 

Its  Nature — Theories  of  Leibniz,  Boscovich  and 
Kant — Criticism . 

Chapter  III.    The  Thomistic  Theory  of  the  Nature 

of  Matter  .         .         .         .         .         -36 

Nature  and  Data  of  Question — History  and  Explana- 
tion of  Hylomorphism — The  Reasons  Advanced  to 
Support  it — Additional  Explanations  of  the  Meaning 
of  '  Matter  '  and  '  Form  ' — Some  Difficulties  Con- 
sidered. 

Chapter  IV.     Quantity     ......       54 

The  Distinction  of  Quantity  and  Substance — Des- 
cartes' View — Reasons  for  Affirming  the  Distinction — 
The  Nature  of  the  Distinction — The  Nature  of 
Quantity  in  Itself — Its  Effects — Opinions — The 
Usual  Thomist  View — Reasons  in  its  Favour — A 
Difficulty  Considered — The  Separability  of  Quantity 
and  Substance  :  Substance  without  Quantity, 
Quantity  without  Substance — A  Peculiarity  of 
Quantity. 

Chapter  V.  The  Continuum  .....  67 
Notion  of  Continuity — Zeno's  Arguments — The  Divisi- 
bility of  the  Continuum — Is  it  Composed  of  Indivi- 
sible Elements  ? — Is  it  Infinitely  Divisible  ? — The 
Parts  of  the  Continuum — The  Indivisibles  of  the 
Continuum — Solution  of  Zeno's  Arguments. 


xii  CONTENTS 


PAGE 


Chapter  VI.     Place  and  Space  ....       78 

I.  Place — Localisation — Kinds  of  Location 

II.  Space — Its  Nature — Opinions — Absolutist,    Sub- 

jectivist,  Intermediate  Theories — The  Void — 
Conclusion  as  to  the  Nature  of  Space. 

III.  The    Occupation   of   Space — Impenetrability — 

Multilocation. 
Chapter  VII.  The  Limits  of  Quantity      .         .         .     103 

The  Infinite — Its  Kinds — The  Possibility  of  Actually 

Infinite  Quantity — Of  an  Actually  Infinite  Multitude. 
Chapter  VIII.     The  Quality  of  Bodies  ;    or  Motion     109 

The  Nature  of  Motion — Action  at  a  Distance — The 

Nature  of  Gravitational  Action. 
Chapter  IX.     Time    .         .         .         .         .         .  117 

Duration — Eternity,  ^vum,  and  Time — Division  of 

Time — Non-Thomistic   Views   as  to  the   Nature  of 

Time — Newton,  Kant,  Leibniz,  Bergson. 
Chapter  X.     Substantial  Change  in  General  .     128 

Meaning   of   Substantial  Change — The   Plurality   of 

Forms — The  Source  of  the  New  Substantial  Form  in 

Generation. 
Chapter  XL     Substantial  Change  in  Chemical  Com- 
position :    The  Question  of  Mixtures       .     141 

Current     Scientific     Views — Philosophical     Views — 

Thomist   Opinions   as   to    the    Permanance    of   the 

Elements  and  Qualities  in  Mixtures. 
Chapter  XII.     The  Individual  .         .         .         -151 

Its  Nature — Opinions — Explanation  of  the  Thomist 

View — Reasons  in  its  Favour — Meaning  of  '  Materia 

Signata  ' — Some  Difficulties  Considered. 
Chapter    XIII.     Some   General   Characteristics   of 

the  Inanimate  World        .         .         .         .164 

Physical  Laws  and  Theories — The  Formation  of  the 

Material  Universe — The  Infinity  and  Eternity  of  the 

Universe. 


Part  II.     The  Philosophy  of  Animate  Nature       .         .     173 
Introduction. 

Division  I.    Life  in  General       .         .         .         .         .178 

Chapter  I.    Vital  Operations  .  .  -179 

Vital  Operations  in  General — Their  Distinctive 
Characteristics — Different  Kinds  of  Vital  Operations 
— Vegetative,  Sensitive,  Intellectual. 

Chapter  II.    The  Principle  of  Life  .         .         .185 

Is  it  One  Only  in  Each  Individual  ? — A  Difficulty — 
Opinions  on  the  Divisibility  of  the  Life-principle — 
Answer  to  the  Question. 


CONTENTS  xiii 

PACE 

Chapter  III.     The  Vital  Powers      .         .         .         .191 
Are  they  Distinct  from  the  Soul  ? — How  are  they 
to  be  Distinguished  from  One  Another  ? 

Chapter  IV.     The  Unity  of  the  Living  Individual     196 
Opinions — The  Thomist  View — Definitions  of  Life. 

Division  II.     Vegetative  Life      .....     200 
Chapter  V.     The  Nature  of  Vegetative  Life  .     201 

Opinions — Mechanism,  Vitalism,  Thomism — Reasons 
in  Favour  of  the  Thomist  View. 
Chapter  VI.     The  Transmission  of  Vegetative  Life     207 
Reproductive   Processes — Thomist   View   of   Repro- 
duction. 

Division  TIL     Sensitive  Life        .         .         .         .         .211 

Chapter  VII.     Cognition  .         .         .         .    1     .     212 

Nature  of  Cognition — S.  Thomas'  View — The  Materi- 
alist and  Idealist  Views — The  Thomist  View  Further 
Explained. 

Chapter  VIII.     The  Process  of  Knowledge     .  .218 

Necessary  Conditions  for  Union  of  Subject  and  Object 
— Their  Assimilation  Involves  Change  in  Both — The 
Intentional  Species — Why  they  are  Necessary — And 
Universally  Necessary — The  Two  Kinds  of  Species  : 
Impressed  and  Expressed — Their  Nature  and  Mode  of 
Production — Their  Precise  Function — Are  Expressed 
Species  Present  in  Every  Cognitive  Act  ? 

Chapter  IX.  Sense  Knowledge  ....  229 
The  Senses  are  Organic — Their  Distinction  and  Num- 
ber— Where  Sensation  Takes  Place — The  Objects  of 
the  Senses — Immediate  and  Mediate  Sense  Objects — 
Can  we  be  said  to  Sense  the  Externality  of  an  Object  ? 
_^~  — The  Inversion  of  the  Retinal  Image — Internal  Sen- 
sibility— The  Sensitive  Appetite. 

Chapter  X.     The  Nature  of  the  Life-principle  in 

Animals      .  .  .  .  .  .  .241 

What  We  Mean  by  '  Animal  ' — Have  they  Sensation  ? 
— Opinions  :  Descartes,  Loeb — The  Thomist  View — 
Is  Sensation  Peculiar  to  Animals  ? — The  Life -principle 
in  Animals  Essentially  Sensitive,  and  their  Substan- 
tial Form  :  so  One  Only — Belonging  to  the  Material 
Order,  yet  Specifically  Distinct  from  that  of  Plants 
— Summary. 

Division  IV.     Intellectual  Life  .         .         .         -251 

Chapter  XL     The  Nature  of  the  Intellect    .  .     252 

Views  as  to  its  Immateriality — S.  Thomas'  Primary 
Reason  for  Holding  it  to  be  So — Its  Objects : 
Common  Formal  Object,  and  Proper  Formal  Object — 
Further  Reasons  for  Regarding  the  Intellect  as  Imma- 
terial— The  Question  of  Its  Activity — Our  Knowledge 
of  Individuals. 


xiv  CONTENTS 

PAGE 

Chapter  XII.     The  Origin  of  Ideas  .         .         .     264 

The  Empiricists — Innate  Ideas — The  Transcendental- 
ists  and  Hegel — The  Difficulty  of  the  Question — The 
Thomist  Solution — The  Active  Intellect — Its  Neces- 
sity and  Function — Summary  of  the  Intellectual 
Process. 

Chapter    XIII.     The   Intellectual   Appetite  ;    The 

Will  .......     272 

Its  Existence — Nature — What  Necessity  is — Freedom 
of  the  Will — History  of  the  Problem — Summary  of 
Opinions — Arguments  in  Favour  of  Liberty — The 
Limits  of  Liberty — Views  on  the  Nature  of  Liberty — 
The  Answer  to  Indeterminism — The  Answer  to 
Psychological  Determinism — Summary  of  results 
arrived  at. 

Chapter  XIV.    The    Nature    of    the    Intellectual 

Soul  in  Man       ......     296 

Its  Substantiality — Its  Spirituality — It  is  the  Substan- 
tial Form — Simple — And  One  Only — Differing  Specifi- 
cally from  that  of  Other  Animals — Reasons  for  this 
View. 

Chapter  XV.     The  Union  of  Soul  and  Body  in  Man     304 
Views   on   the   Question — Monism — Psycho-physical 
Parallelism — Accidental  and  Essential  Union— Reasons 
for  the  Thomist  View — The  Mode  of  the  Union — How 
the  Soul  is  Present  to  the  Body. 

Chapter  XVI.     The    Origin    and    Destiny    of    the 

Human  Soul      ......     312 

Origin — Not  by  Generation  or  Emanation,  but  by 
Creation — The  Transmigration  of  Souls — The  Thomist 
View  of  the  Succession  of  Forms  in  the  Individual — 
Immortality — Opinions — Reasons  for  Thomist  View 
— The  Metaphysical  Argument. 

Chapter  XVII.     The  Origin  of  Life         .         .         .321 
The  Origin  of  Life  on  Earth — Opinions — Spontaneous 
Generation — Two  Forms  of  the  Theory — Their  Possi- 
bility. 

Chapter  XVIII.     Transformism  ....     328 

Preliminary  Remarks — Sketch  of  Evolutionary  The- 
ories— Lamarck — Darwin — The  Materialist  Theory — 
Reasons  which  Exclude  It — Consideration  of  Evolu- 
tionary Theories  in  General. 
Conclusion  .........     344 


MODERN 
THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 


I.    INTRODUCTORY 
SECTION   I 

THE  DEFINITION  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

To  be  Looked  for  in  Philosophy  as  an  Existing  Fact — In  Its 
History — Thales  and  the  Ionic  School — The  Pythagoreans — 
The  Eleatics — Heracleitus — The  Atomists — Anaxagoras — Soc- 
rates and  Plato — Aristotle — Conclusion. 

Most  people  have  the  vaguest  ideas,  if  any,  of  what  philo- 
sophy is,  or  of  what  the  word  philosophy  means.  It  is 
commonly  used  only  in  such  expressions  as  :  'he  took  the 
affair  philosophically,'  in  which,  no  doubt,  it  is  implied  that 
philosophy  helps  a  man  to  bear  up  against  misfortune,  and 
that  philosophers  are  calm  and  unexcitable  people  ;  though 
why  they  should  be  so  does  not  appear.  Consequently,  we 
are  not  much  nearer  any  knowledge  of  what  philosophy  is 
in  itself.  It  is,  however,  essential  for  the  student  to  have, 
at  the  start,  some  notion  of  the  nature  of  the  subject  which 
he  is  about  to  study ;  though  it  is  evident  that  it  can  only 
be  a  rough  and  provisional  one.  He  will  have  to  determine 
for  himself  at  the  end  of  his  study  (if  that  ever  comes) 
whether  it  is  finally  satisfactory.  The  definitions  which  the 
text-books  of  Scholastic  philosophy  put  on  their  opening 
pages  are  often  hurled  at  the  reader's  head  without  much 
proof  that  they  are  correct,  so  that  they  have  to  be  taken 
on  faith,  on  the  authority  of  the  author.    They  thus  fail  to 


2  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

satisfy  the  mind  or  arouse  the  interest.  It  seems  desirable, 
therefore,  that  a  man  should  be  led  to  discover  for  himself 
what  philosophy  is  in  fact.  Now,  everyone  will  agree,  that 
if  we  want  to  discover  the  nature  of  a  thing  the  right  way 
to  do  so  is  to  examine  it.  To  do  this  in  the  case  of  philosophy, 
we  must  see  what  subjects  are  discussed  by  it,  i.e.,  examine 
it  in  the  course  of  its  history.  It  will  hot,  however,  be 
necessary  to  review  its  entire  history,  but  it  will  be  sufficient 
if  we  see  what  its  character  was  during  the  period  of  its 
formation,  which  is  that  of  the  Greek  philosophers  till  the 
time  of  Aristotle. 

Though  it  may  well  be  that  further  precision  might  be 
imported  into  our  definition  by  continuing  our  enquiry 
down  to  the  present  day,  nevertheless,  if  it  be  granted  that 
the  thought  of  Aristotle  and  his  predecessors  is  philosophy 
in  process  of  formation,  we  shall,  by  examining  it,  be  able 
to  discover  what  the  essential  character  of  philosophy  is. 
Just  as  the  child  is  the  father  of  the  man,  and  retains  the 
same  nature  throughout  his  life,  so  Greek  philosophy  is 
the  father  of  modern,  and  thus  in  its  nature  the  same. 
By  following  this  a  posteriori  method  we  shall  avoid  the 
danger  of  making  philosophy  out  to  be  what  we  think  it 
ought  to  be  ;  and  at  the  same  time  the  glimpse  which  will 
thus  be  caught  of  the  beginnings  of  philosophy  will  be  a 
help  and  a  guide  in  the  subsequent  study  of  it. 

The  reason  of  our  choice  of  Greek  philosophy  for  our 
enquiry  is,  that  it  was  in  Greece  that  philosophy  first 
appeared  as  an  autonomous  science,  distinct  from  religion, 
so  that  it  can  be  examined  there  in  a  more  or  less  pure  state. 

Tholes. 

According  to  Aristotle,  whose  opinion  on  this  point  is 
generally  accepted,  Greek  philosophy  begins  with  Thales  of 
Miletus  (c.  624-550  B.C.).  He  and  his  immediate  successors 
were  engaged  on  the  problem  of  discovering  the  nature  of 
the  visible  world  ;  and  this  is  natural,  for  as  soon  as  a  man 
begins  to  think,  that  which  first  attracts  his  attention  is 
the  world  as  presented  to  him  in  sensation,  as  being  the 
most  obvious  aspect  of  it.    The  opinions  of  Thales,  as  far 


THE  DEFINITION  OF  PHILOSOPHY  3 

as  we  know  them  from  tradition,  since  he  left  no  writings, 
are  summarised  in  two  propositions  :  first,  that  water  is 
the  principle  of  all  things  ;  and  secondly,  that  the  earth  is 
a  flat  disc  floating  on  water.  Strange  and  crude  as  these 
statements  sound,  they  have  a  considerable  importance  for 
our  purpose,  since  they  show  that  what  Thales  tried  to  do 
was  to  explain  the  material  constitution  of  the  universe 
by  the  aid  of  reason  alone,  without  appealing  to  religious 
myths,  or  the  intervention  of  the  gods  ;  whose  action  was 
then  normally  invoked  to  account  for  anything  whose 
origin  was  obscure.  He  and  his  successors  were  seeking 
what  was  later  called  the  material  cause  of  the  universe. 
All  the  pre-Socratic  philosophers  followed  the  line  suggested 
by  Thales,  viz.,  that  under  the  multiplicity  of  phenomena, 
of  the  wond  as  perceived  by  sense,  there  must  be  some  one 
permanent  principle.  Just  as  Thales  asserted  that  this 
principle  is  water,  so  his  successors  advanced  other  theories 
as  to  its  nature.  For  Anaximander  it  is  indefinite  matter, 
for  Anaximenes  air,  for  the  Pythagoreans  number,  Jor  the 
Eleatics  being,  for  Heracleitus  fire,  for  Empedocles  the  four 
elements,  and  for  Democritus  atoms. 

The  Ionic  School. 

Thales  was  the  founder  of  what  is  known  as  the  Ionic 
School,  from  the  fact  that  its  three  principal  representatives, 
Thales  himself,  Anaximander  and  Anaximenes,  were  all 
men  of  Ionia.  They  have  been  called  materialists,  though 
they  were  not  so  in  the  modern  sense  of  denying  the  existence 
of  anything  but  matter  :  they  were  simply  concerned  to 
discover  what  the  material  world  was  made  of.  Just  as  a 
child  might  pull  a  toy  to  pieces  to  find  out  what  it  is  made  of, 
so  these  philosophers  tried  to  pull  the  world  to  pieces  with 
their  wits,  and  having  discovered  the  answer,  as  they 
thought,  asked  no  further  questions  about  it. 

The  Pythagoreans. 

The  next  attempt  to  discover  the  primary  constituent  of 
the  material  word  which  calls  for  notice  is  that  made  by 
the  Pythagoreans. 


4  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

Pythagoras  was  born  at  Samos  at  some  time  between 
580  and  570  B.C.  ;  and  in  middle  age  settled  at  Crotona  in 
Italy,  where  he  founded  the  Pythagorean  Society,  which 
was  primarily  a  religious  and  moral  order,  not  a  philosophic 
school.  It  was  closely  connected  with  the  Orphic  Sect,  from 
which  it  took  the  doctrine  of  Metempsychosis,  which  would 
be  better  named  Metasomatosis,  since  it  is  the  theory  that 
souls  pass  from  one  body  to  another.  The  philosophy  of  the 
Pythagoreans  is  the  philosophy  of  number,  for  they  held 
that  number  is  the  stuff  of  which  the  world  is  made.  They 
were  probably  inclined  to  this  strange  opinion  by  their 
mathematical  researches,  for  which  Pythagoras  himself  was 
remarkable.  It  is  thought  that  the  first  book  of  Euclid  is 
substantially  attributable  to  him,  and  he  is  said  to  have 
sacrificed  an  ox  in  honour  of  his  discovery  of  the  47th  proposi- 
tion. Observing  the  world  about  them  the  Pythagoreans 
remarked  that  we  recognise  objects  by  means  of  their 
qualities.  The  various  classes  of  things  have,  however, 
different  qualities,  and  it  seems  at  first  sight  that  there  is 
none  which  is  common  to  all.  Further  examination  shows 
us,  nevertheless,  that  there  is  one  characteristic  which  is 
possessed  by  everything,  that  of  quantity  or  number.  All 
things  are  numerable,  and  can  be  counted.  We  are  reminded 
of  the  saying  of  Galileo  :  '  Philosophy  is  written  in  the  great 
book  which  ever  lies  before  our  eyes — I  mean  the  universe 
— but  we  cannot  understand  it  if  we  do  not  first  learn  the 
language  in  which  it  is  written.  This  book  is  written  in  the 
mathematical  language  '  ;x  though  the  ideas  of  the  Pytha- 
goreans were  much  more  primitive,  and  enveloped  in  an 
atmosphere  of  mysticism.  They  concluded,  indeed,  from 
the  universal  character  of  number  and  from  the  order  and 
harmony  of  the  universe,  not  merely  that  number  is  a  most 
important  element  in  it,  but  that  it  is  its  very  essence,  that 
the  universe  is  made  of  number,  just  as  Thales  had  said  it  is 
made  of  water.  Number  is  the  ultimate,  the  only  reality. 
Further,  from  the  opposition  of  the  determined  and  the 
indeterminate  or  infinite,  are  derived  all  the  fundamental 

1  Galileo  Opere,  Vol.  IV,  p.  171,  quoted  by  Burtt.  Metaphysical 
Foundations  of  Modern  Science,  p.  64. 


THE  DEFINITION  OF  PHILOSOPHY  5 

contrarieties  :  equal  and  unequal,  one  and  multiple,  left  and 
right,  male  and  female,  rest  and  movement,  light  and  dark- 
ness, good  and  evil.  These  dominate  the  nature  and  activity 
of  things,  so  that  every  essence  has  its  number,  and  every 
essence  is  a  number.  This  doctrine,  fantastic  as  it  is — though 
it  has  marked  affinities  with  the  way  in  which  the  universe  is 
regarded  by  modern  mathematical  physics — is  nevertheless 
some  advance  on  the  teaching  of  the  Ionians,  since  it  declares 
that  the  ultimate  material  of  the  universe  is  something  more 
abstract  and  so  more  universal  than  was  allowed  by  them.  It 
belongs,  however,  to  the  same  type  of  enquiry  as  that  of  the 
lcnic  School — the  enquiry,  namely,  as  to  the  stuff  of  which 
the  material  universe  is,  in  the  last  resort,  constructed. 
Consequently,  it  is  on  sense  knowledge  that  all  these  tl  inkers 
rely,  for  it  is  by  the  senses  that  we  are  made  acquainted  with 
material  things ;  so  that  the  first  stage  in  philosophy  is 
similar  to  the  first  stage  in  the  development  of  the  individual 
mind,  when  the  child  is  filled  with  curiosity  as  to  the  things 
around  him,  trying  to  find  out  what  they  are  made  of  by 
sucking  them,  sticking  his  fingers  in  them,  and  pulling  them 
to  pieces  ;  but  hardly  asking  the  reason  of  them  or  using  his 
intellect  about  them.  This  will  be  the  next  stage  in  his 
mental  life,  and  so  it  was  also  in  the  growth  of  philosophy  ; 
for  the  group  of  thinkers  who  now  claim  our  attention  try  to 
investigate  the  reason  of  things,  and  not  merely  the  stuff  of 
which  they  are  made.  They  ask  not  merely  what  things  are 
made  of,  but  why  they  are  as  they  are.  In  this  way  they  are 
of  importance  for  our  present  purpose  since  they  add  a  new 
feature  to  the  conception  of  philosophy. 

The  Eleatics. 

These  philosophers  are  known  as  the  Eleatics,  since  their 
school  was  situated  at  Elea  in  Southern  Italy.  The  founder 
of  this  famous  school  is  said  to  have  been  Xenophanes,  a 
kind  of  troubadour,  but  its  chief  representative  is  Parmen- 
ides,  who  was  born  about  514  B.C.  His  reflections  take  their 
rise  from  the  observation  of  the  changing  character  of  things. 
Since  everything  about  us  is  constantly  changing,  it  seemed 
to  him  that  no  knowledge  of  it  was  possible.     Just  as  in 


6  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

sense  knowledge,  it  is  impossible,  when  looking  at  a  rapidly 
revolving  wheel,  to  have  knowledge  of  the  spokes,  since  they 
have  passed  on  before  they  can  be  seen,  so  knowledge  in 
general  demands  that  its  object  should  be  momentarily,  at 
least,  at  rest,  in  order  that  it  may  be  seized.    If,  then,  there 
is  to  be  knowledge  at  all,  there  must  be  some  unchanging 
reality  underlying  this  shifting  surface  of  the  world.    This 
reality  cannot  be  known  by  the  senses  which  tell  us  only  of 
this  superficial  aspect  of  the  world.    If  it  is  to  be  known  at  all 
then,  it  must  be  by  the  intellect,  which  penetrates  beneath 
the  surface,  and  what  this  sees  everywhere  in  things  is  that 
they  are,  is  their  being.    This,  then,  must  be  the  reality  of 
things,  and  all  that  is  not  being  is  unreal.    Being  is  (i.e.  is 
reality) — not-being  is  not  :    the  first   formulation  of  the 
principle  of  identity,  the  supreme  law  of  thought.     As  he 
considered  further  this  underlying  reality  of  pure  being, 
which  is  wholly  unmixed  with  not-being  or  becoming,  Par- 
menides  saw  that  it  must  be  perfectly  one  and  completely 
immutable  :  it  has  no  beginning  or  becoming  ;  for  if  it  has, 
it  must  come  either  from  being  or  not-being.    If  from  being, 
it  does  not  come  to  be,  since  it  already  is  :  and  from  not-being 
or  nothing,  nothing  comes.    To  maintain  this  position,  how- 
ever, he  was  forced  to  deny  the  testimony  of  the  senses, 
which  show  us  being  in  a  state  of  change,  of  becoming,  and  he 
does  not  scruple  to  do  so.    He  thus  makes  a  distinction  which 
is  henceforth  to  be  of  fundamental  importance  for  philosophy, 
the  distinction  between  sense  and  reason.  True  being  is  known 
to  us  only  by  the  reason,  the  senses  present  to  us  a  world 
which  is  false,  which  is  appearance  only,  and  an  illusion.    By 
a  curious  inconsistency,  however,   which  was  apparently 
unnoticed  by  himself,   Parmenides  conceived  of  this  one 
Being  as  material,  as  occupying  space,  finite  and  spherical. 
That  this  is  an  inconsistency  is  clear,  for  Being  is  a  purely 
abstract  intellectual  concept,  and  cannot  have  any  material 
characteristics  :    for  it  would  thus  be  amenable  to  sense 
knowledge  and  so  be  not-being,  and  like  all  else  that  is 
sensed,  an  illusion.    Nevertheless,  this  inconsistency  in  his 
doctrine  was  the  reason  why,  in  fact,  there  issued  from  it  the 
two  opposing  schools  of  intellectualism  and  materialism. 


THE  DEFINITION  OF  PHILOSOPHY  7 

Since  Being  neither  arises  nor  passes  away,  if  we  adhere 
closely  to  his  doctrine  that  Reality  is  to  be  known  only  by 
the  reason,  and  not  by  the  senses,  we  shall  conclude  that 
there  is  only  one  Being  which  has  no  material  or  sensible 
qualities,  but  is  eternally  the  same — an  absolute  Monism  of 
a  type  which  has  become  familiar  in  modern  philosophy.  If, 
on  the  other  hand,  we  accept  his  statement  that  Being  is 
material,  we  are  led  to  the  doctrine  of  the  absolute  indestruc- 
tibility of  matter ;  matter  has  no  beginning  and  no  end, 
which  is  materialism.  The  first  aspect  of  his  doctrine 
represents,  however,  his  most  striking  and  original  contribu- 
tion to  philosophy,  and  therefore  we  rightly  see  in  him  the 
founder  of  Intellectualism  and  Idealism. 

Zeno. 

The  most  outstanding  of  the  disciples  of  Parmenides  was 
Zeno  (born  about  489  B.C.),  who,  in  support  of  the  theory 
that  Being  is  immutable,  developed  some  famous  arguments 
to  show  that  motion  is  impossible,  and  that  the  very  idea  of 
it  implies  contradiction.  The  best  known  of  these  arguments, 
which  are  dealt  with  in  Cosmology,  is  that  of  Achilles  and  the 
tortoise.  Achilles  and  the  tortoise  run  a  race,  and  if  the 
tortoise  is  given  a  start,  Achilles  can  never  catch  it  up.  For, 
first,  Achilles  has  to  run  to  the  point  from  which  the  tortoise 
started.  When  he  arrives  there,  the  tortoise  will  have  moved 
to  a  further  point ;  and  when  Achilles  reaches  this,  the  tor- 
toise will  have  gone  on  still  further.  This  process  will  be 
indefinitely  repeated,  in  such  a  way  that  the  distance 
between  the  two  will  be  always  diminishing,  but  never  wiped 
out ;  so  that  Achilles  will  never  catch  up  the  tortoise.  This 
and  similar  arguments  are  meant  to  show  that  essential 
contradictions  are  involved  in  our  ideas  of  space  and  time. 

Heracleitus. 

The  antithesis  of  this  static  philosophy  of  the  Eleatics  is 
found,  at  about  the  same  time,  in  the  dynamic  philosophy  of 
Heracleitus  (c.  535-475  B.C.).  He  was  an  aristocrat  of 
Ephesus,  a  sardonic  man,  who  despised  not  only  the  common 
run  of  men,  but  even  men  of  great  reputation,  such  as  Homer 


8  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

and  Hesiod.  As  Parmenides  had  done,  he  sees  that  all  the 
world  around  us  is  perpetually  changing ;  but  instead  of 
rejecting  this  appearance  of  change  as  illusory,  and  asserting 
that  the  reality  must  be  other,  he  accepts  it,  as  itself  the 
basic  reality.  For  him  there  is  no  stability  in  the  universe, 
but  all  is  change.  His  view  is  summed  up  in  the  laconic 
phrase  vavra  pit.  Beneath  this  flux  there  is  no  principle 
which  is  stable  and  permanent,  so  that  we  must  not  shrink 
from  affirming  that  the  thing  which  is,  the  changing  thing, 
at  the  same  time  is  not,  since  there  is  nothing  which  remains 
even  for  a  moment  beneath  the  change.  This  movement, 
this  Becoming,  which  is  pictured  by  Heracleitus  under  the 
form  of  Fire,  is  all  there  is,  and  all  differentiations  of  things 
merge  into  it.  Thus,  no  less  than  Parmenides,  Heracleitus, 
the  originator  of  the  philosophy  of  change,  is  led  to  a  pure 
monism  ;  the  assertion  that  all  reality  is  one  and  undiffer- 
entiated. 

This  fact  suggests  two  important  points  with  regard  to 
the  nature  of  philosophy  : 

i.  The  human  mind  tends  to  reduce  all  things  to  a  simple 
unity  ;  and  that  this  must  be  so,  we  shall  see,  is  accounted  for 
by  S.  Thomas'  theory  of  its  working.  Hence  philosophy  is 
the  business  of  accounting  for  the  many  by  the  one,  of  bring- 
ing particular  cases  under  general  laws,  and  in  the  last  resort 
of  accounting  for  all  things  by  one  principle,  cause  and 
ground.  This  effort,  pushed  to  an  extreme,  ends  in  Pan- 
theism or  Monism,  and  it  is  so  pressed  in  the  two  philosophies 
we  have  just  been  considering.    Extremes  meet.     ' 

2.  But  though  they  are  extremes,  yet  they  are  antithetic- 
ally opposed,  since  one  denies  all  motion,  the  other  all  rest ; 
and  between  these,  philosophy  has  oscillated  ever  since. 
Both  owe  their  attraction  to  what  is,  in  fact,  their  weakness, 
viz.  the  denial  of  one  of  the  elements  in  the  problem.  They 
are  attractive,  being  clear  cut :  weak,  being  inadequate. 

This  suggests  a  further  point,  viz.  that  the  truth  is  likely 
to  be  found  in  neither  of  these,  but  in  a  synthesis  which  com- 
bines them,  and,  in  fact,  the  main  trend  of  philosophy  has 
been  in  the  direction  of  such  a  synthesis,  the  broad  lines  of 
which  were  marked  out  by  Plato  and  Aristotle. 


THE  DEFINITION  OF  PHILOSOPHY  9 

Empedocles. 

A  synthesis  of  this  kind  was  indeed  attempted,  almost  at 
once,  by  Empedocles  (c.  495-435  B.C.),  who  seized  on  Par- 
menides'  principle  of  the  unchangeable  character  of  Being, 
and,  interpreting  it  in  a  materialistic  sense,  asserted  that 
matter  is  indestructible  and  eternal.  On  the  other  hand,  he 
admitted  the  truth  of  the  assertion  of  Heracleitus  that 
change  is  a  reality  ;  in  which  case,  the  change  of  matter  must 
be,  not  an  absolute  coming  into  being  of  it,  which  would  be 
contrary  to  the  Eleatic  principle,  but  a  simple  mixing  and 
unmixing  of  it,  to  form  various  bodies.  There  are,  according 
to  him,  four  fundamental  kinds  of  matter  which,  unchanged 
in  themselves,  combine  to  form  the  various  kinds  of  bodies. 
These  ar,e  earth,  air,  fire  and  water,  which  were  later  known 
as  the  four  elements.  This  theory  marks  a  transition  from 
the  more  or  less  idealistic  doctrines  of  the  Eleatics  and  Hera- 
cleitus to  a  fully  developed  mechanical  and  materialistic 
philosophy,  elaborated  by  Democritus  and  the  Atomists. 

The  Atomists. 

According  to  Democritus  (c.  470-361  B.C.),  if  we  could 
divide  matter  far  enough,  we  should  ultimately  come  to 
indivisible  particles  which,  though  extended,  are  too  small 
to  be  perceptible  by  the  senses ;  these  he  called  atoms. 
Now,  since  they  fill  space  and  have  no  interstices  they  consti- 
tute the  Plenum,  and  correspond  to  the  '  Being  '  of  Par- 
menides.  Side  by  side  with  the  atoms,  which  have  no 
qualities  except  to  fill  space,  Democritus  acknowledges 
another  reality,  the  Vacuum,  which  is  also  extended.  That 
he  must  allow  the  reality  of  this  is  clear,  since  he  admits  the 
reality  of  change,  which  is  nothing  but  the  motion  of  the 
unchangeable  atoms  in  space.  Hence  space  must  exist  and 
be  real,  and  indeed  it  has  all  the  reality  of  atoms,  which  is 
nothing  else  than  extension.  This  Vacuum  corresponds  to 
the  '  Not-Being  '  of  Parmenides.  Thus,  according  to  Demo- 
critus, both  Being  and  Not-Being  are  real,  and  are  extension. 
All  the  motion  in  the  world  is  determined  by  the  nature  of 
the  atoms,  which  is  their  size,  or  weight,  since  there  are  no 
holes  in  them.    Hence  the  bigger  atoms  fall  faster  from  the 


io  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

necessity  of  their  nature :  and  thus,  Democritus  is  led 
explicitly  to  rule  out  any  idea  of  freedom,  or  directing  inten- 
tion in  the  constitution  of  the  world,  or  its  development. 
All  comes  about  by  a  blind  mechanical  motion.  It  originates 
by  chance,  and  it  develops  by  the  necessary  law  of  its  nature. 
In  these  theories  the  question  as  to  the  origin  of  the  world  is, 
at  least  obliquely,  answered.  How  did  it  come  to  be  ?  It 
did  not,  since  matter  is  eternal  and  indestructible,  and  the 
force  which  moves  it  is  simply  natural  to  it. 

Anaxagoras< 

This  answer,  however,  did  not  satisfy  Anaxagoras  (c.  500- 
428  B.C.)  ;  for  he  saw  that  blind  forces  and  mechanical 
motion  could  not  .produce  such  an  ordered  and  harmonious 
universe  as  that  which  we  see.  Nature,  moreover,  shows 
design  :  all,  or  many,  of  its  operations  being  directed  to  the 
production  of  ends.  Such  order  and  purpose,  he  thought, 
could  only  be  produced  by  an  agent  which  is  rational,  non- 
physical  and  incorporeal — an  intelligence  or  Nous.  Aristotle 
praises  him  for  this  entirely  original  contribution  to  philo- 
sophy :  '  he  seemed  like  a  sober  man  in  contrast  with  the 
random  talk  of  his  predecessors.'1 

He  is  thus  the  first  to  show  that  philosophy  must  include, 
beside  the  discussion  as  to  the  composition  and  genesis  of 
bodies  materially  speaking,  an  investigation  as  to  the  ulti- 
mate final  and  efficient  causes  of  the  universe  ;  and  more- 
over the  first  to  make  clear  the  distinction  between  mind 
and  matter,  and  between  blind  mechanical  chance  and 
purpose. 

Thus  closes  the  first  period  of  philosophic  thought  in 
which  philosophy  has  chiefly  concerned  itself  with  the 
attempt  to  discover  the  composition  of  the  material  world  ; 
and  the  discussion  of  its  most  obvious  elements,  matter  and 
motion.  Thus  philosophy,  in  its  infancy,  took  stock  of  the 
world  of  sense  about  it,  and  hardly  gave  a  thought  to  itself, 
to  man  who  observes  this  world,  and  the  mind  by  whose 
means  he  does  so.    The  consideration  of  these  things  was 

1  The  Works  of  Aristotle,  translated  into  English,  Vol.  VIII.  (Oxford, 
1908.)    Metaphysics,  Bk.  I,  98^18. 


THE  DEFINITION  OF  PHILOSOPHY  n 

now  to  be  the  main  business  of  Greek  philosophy,  and 
the  link  between  the  new  and  old  is  to  be  found  in  the 
introduction  of  the  all-ordering  Intelligence  postulated  by 
Anaxagorus. 

The  Sophists. 

Philosophy  did  not,  however,  pass  at  a  bound  from  child- 
hood to  mature  manhood ;  it  had  first  to  pass  through  a 
period  of  stagnation  and  even  of  decadence — to  sow  its 
wild  oats. 

This  is  the  period  of  the  Sophists,  for  whom  philosophy 
was  a  meie  means  of  getting  on  in  the  world.  It  became 
therefore  their  slave  instead  of  their  mistress,  and  they  did 
not  aim  at  discovering  truth,  but  only  at  finding  arguments 
which  would  flatten  out  any  opponent.  This  led  naturally 
enough  to  Scepticism — or  doubt  as  to  the  possibility  of 
arriving  at  any  knowledge — and  Subjectivism — the  con- 
tention that  that  is  true  which  appears  so  to  me,  or  to  any 
individual.  Among  the  Sophists  perhaps  the  most  famous 
are  Protagoras  and  Gorgias.  The  propositions  which  the 
latter  undertook  to  prove  :  (i)  that  nothing  exists,  (2)  that 
if  anything  exists,  it  cannot  be  known  and  (3)  that  if  it  can 
be  known,  the  knowledge  of  it  cannot  be  communicated, 
were  typical  of  Scepticism  ;  and  the  dictum  of  Protagoras, 
'  man  is  the  measure  of  all  things  ;  of  what  is,  that  it  is  ;  of 
what  is  not,  that  it  is  not ; '  of  Subjectivism.  These  two, 
Scepticism  and  Subjectivism,  are  twin  diseases  to  which 
philosophy  ever  since  has  been  subject. 

Socrates. 

A  new  era  of  health  and  vigour  opens  with  the  teaching  of 
Socrates  after  this  short  period  of  decadence  ;  for  the  Greek 
mind  was  still  young  and  strong,  and  could  not  long  succumb 
to  the  enervating  cynicism  of  the  Sophists.  The  spokesman 
of  the  revolt  was  an  artisan,  a  rough  and  ugly  fellow,  who 
loved  to  argue  at  the  street  corners  and  let  the  wind  of  com- 
mon sense  sweep  away  the  pretensions  and  high-flown 
arguments  of  the  Sophists.  This  Socrates,  unlike  the  earlier 
philosophers,  was  not  so  much  concerned  with  the  nature, 


12  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

origin  and  working  of  the  material  world,  as  with  man  hin> 
self.  He  regarded  philosophy  as  the  means  which  a  man 
should  use  in  order  to  lead  the  life  which  will  satisfy  his 
highest  aspirations — it  was  to  serve  as  the  guide  of  life,  just 
as  Christianity,  in  so  far  as  it  lays  down  a  moral  law,  is 
intended  to  do  for  us.  His  interest  in  it,  therefore,  was 
much  more  poignant  and  personal  than  that  of  the  somewhat 
academic  speculations  which  we  have  just  reviewed.  Now, 
in  order  that  we  may  lead  the  '  good  life,'  we  must  know 
what  good  is  :  and  Socrates  maintained  that  all  knowledge 
is  knowledge  through  concepts.  Concepts,  moreover,  are  the 
notions  we  have,  not  of  particular  things,  but  of  the  essences 
or  natures  of  things  ;  and  these  concepts  we  express  in 
definitions  which  are  absolutely  fixed  and  unchangeable. 
Hence  the  Sophistic  notion  that  the  truth  will  vary  according 
to  the  mind  of  the  individual  is  altogether  repugnant  to 
Socrates  ;  and  he  insists  that  it  is  to  be  judged  by  an 
absolute  standard,  not  by  any  subjective  impressions.  Just 
as  in  measures  the  State  enforces  a  standard  of  measurement; 
and  a  draper  is  not  able  to  assign  any  number  of  inches 
which  he  pleases  to  a  yard  ;  so  in  the  realm  of  thought  we 
shall  have  an  absolute  concept  of  Good,  by  means  of  which 
we  are  to  test  the  goodness  of  any  particular  action.  Since 
it  is  absolute  and  unchangeable  it  cannot  be  identified  with 
what  seems  to  be  good  for  a  particular  man  at  a  given  moment, 
viz.  what  is  useful  or  pleasant  for  him,  but  must  be  equally 
applicable  to  all  men  at  all  times  ;  and  so  may  clash  with 
what  seems  good  at  the  moment.  He  thus  vindicated  the 
supremacy  of  absolute  Good.  We  know  what  this  good  is  if 
we  think  rightly.  Now,  no  man  can  desire  what  is  evil  or 
bad  for  him  ;  if  he  does  but  come  to  the  knowledge  of  the 
good,  by  right  thinking,  he  will  follow  it.  Virtue,  therefore, 
is  to  be  identified  with  knowledge,  and  sin  with  ignorance. 
Hence  the  attainment  of  knowledge  is  of  supreme  importance, 
and  consequently,  it  is  necessary  to  discover  the  laws  of 
knowledge  in  general.  The  attempt  which  Socrates  made  to 
do  this  paved  the  way  for  the  systematic  Logic  of  Aristotle. 
He  thus  brings  within  the  realm  of  philosophy  three  regions 
unclaimed,  and  unexplored,  by  it  before  :  the  investigation 


THE  DEFINITION  OF  PHILOSOPHY  13 

of  the  essences  or  natures  of  things,  the  enquiry  into  the 
workings  of  the  human  mind,  and  the  discussion  of  right 
conduct  for  man.  It  remained  for  Plato  and  Aristotle  to 
perfect  and  systematise  his  investigations  in  these  three 
regions,  and  so  to  develop  fully  what  are  now  known  as  the 
sciences  of  Logic,  Psychology,  Metaphysics  and  Ethics. 

A  short  account  of  the  work  of  these  two  great  thinkers  is 
required  in  order  that  we  may  have  a  comprehensive  idea  of 
what  philosophy  meant  to  the  Greeks. 

Plato  (427-347). 

Though  Plato  is  one  of  the  greatest  philosophers  in  the 
history  of  the  world,  his  genius  and  originality  did  not  only, 
or  even  chiefly,  consist  in  the  introduction  of  new  ideas  ;  but 
rather  in  the  co-ordination  and  transformation  of  the  work 
of  the  earlier  thinkers.  What  is  true  of  Plato  in  this  respect 
is  true  also  of  all  the  great  philosophers,  with  the  possible 
exception  of  Kant.  Their  originality  always  shows  itself 
rather  in  the  new  perspective  in  which  they  viewed  the 
problems  which  had  been  discussed  by  their  predecessors, 
and  the  developments  which  they  gave  to  them,  than  in  the 
propounding  of  novel  doctrines.  At  the  first  glance,  the 
history  of  philosophy  seems  to  be  but  a  record  of  conflicting 
opinions  without  any  unity  ;  but  a  closer  scrutiny  will  show 
that  there  has  iDeen  all  through  it  a  development  of  certain 
great  central  ideas,  though,  of  course,  with  setbacks  and 
aberrations.  All  the  great  philosophical  systems  have  their 
roots  deep  in  the  past,  and  embody  a  uniform  tradition. 
This  tradition  is  first  found  clearly  and  explicitly  in  Plato 
and  Aristotle  ;  and  consequently  this  philosophy  has  rightly 
been  called  the  '  philosophia  perennis.' 

So  Plato,  standing  as  it  were  on  the  shoulders  of  Par- 
menides  and  Socrates,  sees  even  more  vividly  than  they  had 
done,  that  the  philosopher's  work  is  to  contemplate  being, 
and  the  essences  of  things.  Now  the  characteristic  of  these 
essences  is  that  they  are  universal.  The  idea  and  the  nature 
of  Man,  of  Triangle,  and  so  on,  apply  to  all  men,  all  triangles, 
regardless  of  their  individual  differences.  But  Plato  asks  : 
are  these  ideas  merely  in  our  minds,  or  have  they  some  reality 


14  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

apart  from  them  ?  He  is  convinced  that  they  have,  though 
not  in  the  world  known  by  the  senses,  for  there  they  are 
found  particularised  and  limited.  Thus  he  concludes  that 
their  reality  must  lie  in  some  super-sensible  world  where  the 
Man-in-Himself,  the  Triangle-in-Itself  must  subsist  in  their 
own  right.  This  the  realm  of  the  Ideas  which  alone  is  truly 
real :  and  it  follows  that  the  individual  things  which  we 
see  and  handle  are  not  real  except  in  so  far  as  the  Ideas  are 
reflected  in  them.  They  are  feeble  and  deceitful  copies  of 
reality,  and  the  object,  not  of  science,  but  of  opinion.  They 
are  a  number  of  mirrors  reflecting  images  in  the  sky,  and 
indeed  distorting  ones,  such  as  those  convex  and  concave 
ones  seen  at  fairs  ;  for  matter,  indeed,  distorts  the  Ideas — 
the  Reality  itself  is  immaterial — matter  is  illusory,  and  is, 
in  a  sense,  that  which  is  not.  This  theory  of  the  Ideas 
involves  consequences  in  other  directions  ;  and  especially  in 
Psychology.  For  if,  as  is  the  fact,  we  have  knowledge  of  the 
Ideas,  this  knowledge  cannot  have  come  to  us  by  way  of  the 
senses,  which  tell  us  only  of  the  illusory  material  phenomena, 
and  must,  therefore,  have  come  directly  from  the  Ideas 
themselves,  i.e.  the  Ideas  must  be  already  in  our  minds 
before  we  begin  our  sense  life,  before  we  were  born.  In  a 
former  life,  before  the  soul  was  imprisoned  in  the  body,  it 
contemplated  the  Ideas,  and  has  brought  fragments  of  this 
knowledge  with  it  into  the  world. 

Our  birth  is  but  a  sleep  and  a  forgetting  ; 
The  soul  that  rises  with  us,  our  life's  star, 

Hath  had  elsewhere  its  setting, 

And  cometh  from  afar. 

(Wordsworth.    Ode,  "  Intimations  of  Immortality.") 

We  are  thus  led  to  a  psychological  dualism — man  is  a  soul, 
or  mind,  forcibly  united  to  a  body. 

Plato,  therefore,  appears  first  and  foremost  as  a  meta- 
physician, considering  the  fundamental  reality  and  being  of 
things  ;  his  psychological  and  cosmological  theories  being,  in 
the  main,  corollaries  which  followed  from  his  metaphysical 
one.  Nevertheless,  he  did  not  regard  metaphysics  as  mere 
speculation,  for  he  had  a  profound  belief  that,  by  philosophy, 
man  can  be  enabled  to  live  the  perfect  life.  Thus  he  expanded 


THE  DEFINITION  OF  PHILOSOPHY  15 

and  amplified  the  moral  teaching  of  Socrates,  showing  that 
'  the  good  life  '  is  to  be  found,  not  in  pleasure,  nor  even  in 
virtue,  but  in  union  with  the  Idea  of  Good  ;  and  it  is  to  this 
that  metaphysical  contemplation  is  directed.  So,  in  the  light 
of  his  metaphysical  principles,  he  discusses  individual  and 
social  morality,  and  the  constitution  of  the  perfect  society 
or  Republic,  where,  since  the  parts  are  for  the  good  of  the 
whole,  all  the  individuals  will  be  absolutely  subordinated  to 
the  State. 

Aristotle  (385-322). 

For  our  purpose,  which  is  to  discover  the  nature  of  philo- 
sophy from  the  conceptions  which  the  great  Greek  thinkers 
formed  of  it,  it  will  not  be  necessary  to  set  out  in  detail  the 
various  doctrines  with  which  Aristotle  enriched  it ;  but  it  is 
sufficient  to  show  that,  in  his  view,  the  aim  of  philosophy  is 
to  get  to  the  very  heart  of  things  ;  his  doctrine,  wide  as  it  is 
in  its  scope,  being  still  more  remarkable  for  its  profundity. 
The  subject  of  philosophy,  he  says,  has  always  been,  is  now, 
and  always  will  be  the  question  what  is  being,  what  is  sub- 
stance, or  as  we  should  say  nowadays,  what  is  reality  ?  In 
answering  this  question,  philosophy  cannot  be  satisfied  with 
any  reply  which  leaves  some  being  unexplained  ;  it  must 
reach  down  to  the  first  causes  and  reasons  of  being — of  all 
being,  whether  material  or  mental,  universal  or  particular, 
mutable  or  immutable.  Thus  the  earlier  philosophies  had 
considered  material  being  exclusively ;  Parmenides  and 
Heracleitus  excluded  mutable  and  immutable  being  respec- 
tively ;  even  Plato  had  extruded  the  world  of  sense  and  the 
individual  from  reality,  pronouncing  it  illusory.  So  according 
to  Aristotle  being  is  of  many  kinds,  and  not  all  one,  as  Par- 
menides would  have  it.  To  justify  this  he  works  out  his  great 
doctrines  of  the  analogy  of  being,  and  the  categories,  which 
will  exclude  Pantheism  ;  of  potentiality  and  act,  which  will 
account  for  motion  and  change  ;  of  the  four  causes  among 
which  the  final  cause  is  first  and  dominant.  It  is  end  which 
makes  the  agent  act,  and  determines  the  form  or  nature  of 
the  thing  produced,  which  form  in  its  turn  puts  its  impress 
on  matter,  making  it  of  a  certain  kind.    Now  the  end  to  be 


16  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

attained  is  not  something  material,  but  is  mental :  it  is  an 
idea,  as  is  clearly  seen  in  the  case  of  the  sculptor  carving  a 
statue ;  and  it  is  one  and  the  same  idea  in  different  states 
which  makes  him  work,  which  guides  his  action,  and  is 
embodied  in  the  finished  sculpture.  Here,  then,  we  see  that 
Aristotle  agrees  with  Plato  in  asserting  that  the  primary 
constituent  of  reality  is  form  or  idea,  but  now  it  is  incarnate 
in  material  things,  not  subsisting  separated  from  them.  It 
is  for  this  reason  that  Aristotle  has  been  counted  as  the 
opponent  of  Plato  :  but,  though  he  criticises  severely  the 
subsisting  forms  of  Platonism,  his  aim  is  not  to  break  down 
the  essential  features  of  Platonic  idealism,  but  rather  to 
complete  his  master's  work.  Both  agree  that  reality  is 
fundamentally  ideal  or  mental.  Plato,  however,  since  he 
divorces  his  Ideas  from  the  world  of  sense  in  fact  removes 
all  reality  from  it  also,  while  Aristotle  by  embodying  forms 
in  matter  restores  reality  to  material  things  ;  but  is  obliged 
to  admit  that  the  forms  are,  when  in  this  state,  limited  and 
imperfect.  Both  form  and  matter,  moreover,  owe  their  very 
being  to  the  fact  that  they  are  directed  to  the  same  end,  to 
something  other,  and  more  perfect,  than  themselves,  to 
something  which  is  more  detached  from  matter,  more  formal 
and  more  actual ;  and  so  in  the  last  resort  to  something 
wholly  formal,  wholly  actual  and  perfect,  which  has,  there- 
fore, the  nature  of  mind,  or  rather  of  thought.  This  is  the 
Aristotelean  God,  from  which  the  whole  world  hangs  sus- 
pended by  desire  :  Being,  which  desires  nothing  but  itself, 
and  thinks  nothing  but  itself,  for  it  is  wholly  perfect.  It  is 
in  this  way  that  Aristotle  arrives  at  the  ultimate  cause  and 
ground  of  all  reality  :  to  search  for  which  is,  in  his  view,  the 
proper  business  of  philosophy. 

Since  the  Thomist  philosophy,  with  which  we  are  to  deal, 
owes  more  to  Aristotle  than  to  any  other  single  thinker,  it 
may  not  be  out  of  place  to  add  a  few  details  with  regard  to 
the  life  of  the  man  whom  S.  Thomas  calls,  without  qualifica- 
tion, the  Philosopher.  Aristotle  was  born  in  385-4  B.C.  at 
Stagira,  a  seaport  of  Chalcidice.  His  father  was  court  doctor 
to  the  King  of  Macedonia,  but  died  while  his  son  was  still  a 
boy.    He  was  later  sent  by  his  guardian  to  study  at  Athens, 


THE  DEFINITION  OF  PHILOSOPHY  17 

where,  at  the  age  of  seventeen,  he  joined  the  Academy — 
Plato's  school  there.  Here  he  remained  as  Plato's  pupil  and 
disciple  till  the  latter's  death.  He  was  twice  married,  and 
for  five  years  was  tutor  to  Alexander  the  Great.  Possibly  it 
was  his  life  at  court  which  made  him  more  careful  of  his 
personal  appearance  than  are  the  generality  of  philosophers, 
for  it  is  said  that  he  was  noticeably  well-dressed.  On 
Alexander's  succession  to  the  throne  of  Macedonia  he  returned 
to  Athens,  where  he  established  a  philosophic  school  in  a 
place  called  the  Lyceum.  Here  his  habit  of  walking  up  and 
down  among  the  trees,  discussing  abstruse  philosophical 
questions  with  his  pupils,  gained  the  name  of  Peripatetics 
for  his  disciples.  In  the  evening  he  explained  less  difficult 
subjects  to  a  larger  audience.  In  323  there  was  an  outburst 
of  anti-Macedonian  feeling  at  Athens  :  and  Aristotle,  having 
been  so  closely  associated  with  the  Macedonian  court,  was  in 
some  danger.  He  therefore  retired  to  the  fortress  of  Chalcis  ; 
to  prevent  the  Athenians  committing  another  crime  against 
philosophy,  as  he  said,  referring  to  the  execution  of  Socrates. 
He  died  at  Chalcis  in  the  following  year. 

Conclusions. 

We  are  now  in  a  position  to  draw  together  the  facts  which 
we  have  noted  in  our  account  of  the  genesis  of  philosophy, 
and  so  to  determine  what  philosophy  really  was  in  the  time 
of  the  Greeks  ;  which  will  tell  us  what  it  is,  in  its  essence, 
to-day.  Now  it  is  evident,  in  the  first  place,  that  all  these 
investigators  were  seeking,  not  a  method  of  making  or  doing 
something,  as  an  artist  or  an  engineer  might  be,  but  some  sort 
of  knowledge.  Knowledge  in  itself,  and  for  its  own  sake, 
seems  to  be  their  aim,  and  they  range  over  a  wide  tract  of 
country  in  their  hunt  for  it.  The  Ionians  want  to  know  what 
the  material  world  is  made  of  ;  and  answer  :  material  stuff 
of  one  sort  or  another,  which  is  the  uniform  basis  of  all 
bodies.  The  Pythagoreans,  in  answer  to  the  same  question, 
say  it  is  a  universal  quality  of  matter  :  the  Eleatics,  examin- 
ing it  more  searchingly  still,  say  it  is  the  unchangeable  being 
of  matter ;  Heracleitus,  the  constant  movement  and 
becoming  of  it.  Empedocles  and  the  Atomists  try  to  reconcile 


18  MODERN  THOMOSTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

these  last  two  answers,  while  Anaxagoras  points  out  that 
there  is  something  in  the  material  world  which  is  not 
material,  viz.  order.  This  must  tend  to  some  end  and  be 
produced  by  some  mind.  So  for  the  first  time  a  new  field  is 
opened  up  for  examination  by  philosophy  :  it  must  know 
what  mind  is.  But  man  has  mind,  says  Socrates,  so  philo- 
sophy must  ask  what  man  is.  With  Plato  the  interest  of 
philosophy  centres  in  this  question  of  the  nature  of  mind, 
and  of  concepts — of  the  immaterial ;  while  with  Aristotle 
the  balance  is  restored  and  material  nature,  man,  mind  and 
God  all  come  within  the  scope  of  the  enquiry. 

None  of  these  men,  it  is  to  be  noted,  tried  to  answer  these 
questions  by  an  appeal  to  any  revelation,  to  myth,  or  religi- 
ous knowledge  of  any  kind  ;  but  attempted  to  extract  the 
answer  by  using  their  reason  ;  and  they  used  it  almost  with- 
out reference  to  sensible  observation  and  experiments.  Why 
was  this  ?  Clearly  because  they  were  convinced  that  the 
thing  they  sought  lay  deeper  in  the  heart  of  the  world  than 
the  superficial  aspect  of  things,  of  which  alone  the  senses 
could  tell  them.  They  were  seeking  the  underlying  causes 
of  things,  and  this  is  the  special  point  of  view  from  which 
philosophy  discusses  its  multifarious  objects,  which  are  dealt 
with  from  another  aspect,  by  special  sciences,  such  as  chem- 
istry, biology,  zoology,  and  so  on.  It  intends  to  go  further 
into  their  nature  than  these  do,  and  not  to  rest  content  until 
it  has  uncovered  the  absolutely  fundamental  reasons  of  them 
all.  Thus  the  early  philosophies  were  not  concerned  to  find 
out,  e.g.,  of  what  the  world,  as  at  present  constituted,  is 
composed,  as  chemistry  is ;  but  what  were  its  primary 
constituents  :  or  again,  in  the  case  of  man,  they  were  not 
concerned,  for  example,  with  his  anatomy,  but  whether,  in 
the  last  resort,  he  is  spiritual  or  material,  intelligent,  and  so 
on.  So  philosophy  is  distinguished,  on  the  one  hand,  from 
any  knowledge  which  may  be  gained  through  religion ;  and 
on  the  other,  from  that  which  may  be  gained  from  what  we 
now  call  the  Natural  Sciences.  Secondly,  it  uses  in  its 
investigations  only  natural  reason,  not  faith,  nor  yet  sensible 
experience  as  such.  Thirdly,  it  excludes  nothing  from 
its  examination,   but  includes   all  things  in  heaven  and 


THE   DEFINITION   OF   PHILOSOPHY  19 

earth,  man  and  God,  in  its  enquiry ;  and  yet  is  dis- 
tinguished from  all  the  special  sciences  which  study  any  of 
these  things,  by  its  special  point  of  view,  which  is  to  discover 
the  basic  reason  of  all :  and  thus  philosophy  is  not  to  be 
identified  with  any  of  them  singly,  or  all  of  them  together. 
All  this  can  be  summed  up  in  the  one  phrase,  which  is  the 
real  definition  of  philosophy  :  It  is  the  scientific  knowledge 
of  all  things  gained  through  consideration  by  the  natural 
light  of  reason,  of  their  fundamental  reasons  or  causes. 
Books  to  consult  : 

W.  Stace,  A  Critical  History  of  Greek  Philosophy.  (Mac- 
millan.)  To  which  the  foregoing  account  owes  much.  It 
also  includes  a  discussion  as  to  the  nature  of  philosophy. 

J.  Maritain,  Introduction  to  Philosophy.    (Sheed  and  Ward.) 

Burnet,  Early  Greek  Philosophy.    (Macmillan.) 

W.  D.  Ross,  Aristotle.     (Methuen.) 

A.  E.  Taylor,  Plato :  the  Man  and  his  Work.    (Methuen.) 


SECTION   II 

THE   DIVISION   OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Aristotle  discusses  the  division  of  the  sciences  in  the  first 
chapter  of  the  sixth  book  of  the  Metaphysics.  Here  he  divides 
them  into  three  great  classes  :  practical,  productive  and 
theoretical  (i025b25).  The  first  seek  knowledge  for  the 
conduct  of  life  ;  the  second  in  order  to  make  something 
which  is  either  useful  or  beautiful ;  the  third  seek  knowledge 
for  its  own  sake.  If  Logic  had  to  be  put  within  this  scheme, 
it  would  rank  as  a  theoretical  science,  but  Aristotle  considers 
it  to  be  not  a  science  on  its  own  account,  but  a  necessary 
preliminary  to  all  knowledge,  for,  as  he  remarks  :    aroirov 

ajxa    farelv    €iri(TTTJ[j.-qv    kcu    rpoirov    eiruTTrjiArjs — '  it    IS    absurd    to 

seek  at  the  same  time  knowledge  and  the  way  of  attain- 
ing knowledge  !  '  (Met.  995ai3.)  Since,  as  we  have  seen, 
philosophy  is  scientific  knowledge,  it  will  come  under 
the  classification  given  above,  though  it  is  evident  that 
philosophy  is  not  productive.  The  theoretical  sciences  are, 
according  to  Aristotle,  physics,  which  deals  with  all  things 
which  are  inseparable  from  matter,  but  not  unchangeable ; 
mathematics,  which  deals  with  things  that  are  unchangeable 
though  probably  not  separable,  but  embodied  in  matter, 
and  metaphysics,  which  deals  with  things  that  are  both 
separable  and  unchangeable. 

Now  Aristotle  treats  the  whole  body  of  knowledge  which 
can  be  gained  of  these  subject  matters  as  philosophical,  since 
experimental  science,  as  we  now  have  it,  had  not  then  been 
constituted  ;  but,  in  process  of  time,  sciences  have  one  by 
one  detached  themselves  from  their  parent,  philosophy,  and 
set  up  business  on  their  own  account.  So  Mathematics, 
Biology,  Astronomy,  and,  last  of  all,  Psychology  are  now 
reckoned  as  independent  sciences,  leaving  behind  them, 


THE  DIVISION  OF  PHILOSOPHY  21 

however,  sciences  which  treat  of  their  various  spheres  purely 
philosophically  ;  so  that  we  have,  for  example,  mathematical 
philosophy,  which  considers  the  basis  or  foundations  of 
Mathematics  ;  and  the  philosophy  of  life  and  mind  which 
considers  the  ultimate  origin  and  nature  of  these.  With 
certain  modifications,  then,  the  general  scheme  which  Aris- 
totle lays  down  for  the  classification  of  the  philosophical 
sciences  still  holds  good,  and  we  shall  see  later  that  it  is  the 
most  scientific  division  which  can  be  made.  For  this  reason, 
and  because  it  is  fairly  generally  adhered  to  by  Scholastic 
writers,  it  will  be  convenient  for  us  to  follow  it.  We  thus 
begin  by  considering  the  material  world  in  general,  and  then 
the  two  great  classes  of  material  things,  the  inanimate  and 
living  ones.  The  first  two  sections  here  are  often  grouped 
together  under  the  name  of  Cosmology  ;  while  that  of  Psy- 
chology is  given  to  the  third.  As  Mathematical  Philosophy 
is  never  treated  separately  by  Scholastics  of  the  present  day, 
it  will  be  unnecessary  for  us  to  devote  a  special  section  to  it, 
but  several  questions  which  really  belong  to  it  will  be  ex- 
plained in  Cosmology.  The  last  part  of  our  explanation 
deals  with  Metaphysics.  Since  this  explanation  is  confined 
to  speculative  philosophy,  it  takes  no  account  of  Ethics, 
which  is  evidently '  practical '  in  Aristotle's  sense  of  the  word. 
(For  this  last,  see  Cronin,  The  Science  of  Ethics. — Gill.) 


II.  THE   PHILOSOPHY    OF   NATURE 

Part    I.— COSMOLOGY :    THE    PHILOSOPHY  OF 
INANIMATE    NATURE 

INTRODUCTION 

As  we  have  seen,  Aristotle  regards  as  the  object  of  our  study 
in  this  part  of  philosophy,  not  so  much  material  things  qua 
material,  but  qua  changeable  ;  for  it  is  this  characteristic 
particularly  which  differentiates  them  from  the  objects  of 
mathematics.  In  this  he  is  followed  by  S.  Thomas,  who  says 
that  physics  deals  with  mobile  being,  i.e.  being  which  is 
subject  to  motion  or  change.  The  first  question  we  shall 
have  to  ask,  therefore,  is  :  What  is  this  mobile  or  changeable 
being  ?  On  taking  a  general  view  of  the  world  of  nature, 
that  which  strikes  us  immediately  in  it  is  its  variety  :  the 
innumerable  forms  of  plant  and  animal  life,  the  changing 
clouds,  the  very  stones  and  kinds  of  soil  are  all  different.  If 
we  look  up  to  the  starry  sky,  the  same  variety  and  multi- 
plicity are  evident.  It  is  this  aspect  which  is  emphasised  in 
the  name  changeable,  or  mobile,  being  which  is  given  to  the 
object  of  Cosmology,  for  without  variety  there  could  be  no 
change,  so  that  to  call  this  being  changeable  supposes  it  to 
be  various.  Is  this  epithet,  applied  to  nature,  a  correct  one  ? 
Such  is  the  first  question  which  we  must  ask  ;  and  as  we 
have  seen,  it  met  with  an  unhesitating  negative  from  Par- 
menides.  It  is,  in  fact,  the  central  question  of  Cosmology, 
and  recurs  all  through  it.  It  will  only  be  completely  answered 
when  we  have  considered  it  in  all  its  forms,  so  that  at  this 
stage  we  cannot  give  more  than  a  preliminary  and  tentative 
reply.  It  is  worth  doing  this,  however,  in  order  to  strike  at 
the  very  start  the  key-note  of  the  whole  discussion,  and  to 
bring  into  prominence  the  principles  which  must  be  taken 


COSMOLOGY  23 

into  account  in  any  solution  of  the  cosmological  problem. 
Our  reply  at  this  stage  will  be  on  the  level  of  ordinary 
common  sense  ;  and  it  might  be  thought  that,  from  this 
point  of  view,  it  is  unnecessary  even  to  ask  whether  the 
world  is  composed  of  a  variety  of  things  or  not,  since  it 
seems  obvious  that  it  is  ;  as  Stevenson  says  : 

The  world  is  so  full  of  a  number  of  things, 

That  I'm  sure  we  should  all  be  as  happy  as  kings. 

This  common-sense  view  is  known,  in  philosophy,  as  plural- 
ism. It  is,  however,  not  accepted  by  a  great  number  of  those 
who  have  given  attention  to  this  subject ;  who  say  that  all 
things  in  the  world  are  of  the  same  kind,  and  even  that  they 
do  not  differ  from  one  another  as  units  ;  so  that  there  are 
not,  for  example,  many  trees,  but  one  tree.  This  last  which, 
when  thus  baldly  stated,  sounds  quite  absurd,  is  in  fact 
based  on  certain  theories  as  to  the  nature  of  reality,  such  as 
Pantheism,  which  we  shall  have  to  consider  later  ;  when  the 
denial  of  the  numerical  distinction  of  bodies  will  evidently 
stand  or  fall  with  the  theory  on  which  it  is  based.  We  may, 
however,  notice  at  once  that  we  have  the  testimony  of  our 
own  consciousness  to  vouch  for  our  distinction  from  other 
men,  since  we  are  conscious  of  initiating  our  own  actions  and 
of  doing  so,  sometimes  at  least,  without  any  dependence  on 
other  men.  If,  then,  we  are  independent  in  action,  we  must 
be  also  independent  beings,  so  that  there  are  at  least  some 
bodies,  viz.  our  own,  which  are  numerically  distinct  from 
each  other. 

We  are  here  more  directly  concerned  with  the  opinion 
that  all  bodies  are  of  the  same  nature,  than  with  that  which 
maintains  that  they  do  not  differ  as  individuals,  for  the 
former  view  is  founded  on  observation  of  the  material  world, 
not  on  some  preconceived  theory  of  reality.  It  is  an  opinion 
which  has  been  widely  held  since  the  advent,  or  rather  the 
popularisation,  of  evolutionary  ideas.  Darwin's  theory  of 
the  gradual  development  of  one  species  from  another  has 
naturally  been  extended  to  the  whole  world,  and  an  attempt 
been  made  to  show  that  everything  is  but  a  superficial  modi- 
fication of  some  primordial  matter.  This  doctrine  goes  by 
the  name  of  Materialistic  Monism,  and  was  expounded  as  a 


24  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

scientific  theory  by  Haeckel,  and  as  a  philosophical  one  by 
Herbert  Spencer,  to  name  two  out  of  many.  It  is  also 
sometimes  called  Naturalism. 

As  has  been  remarked,  it  is  impossible  at  this  stage  to  do 
more  than  to  meet  this  theory  at  the  level  of  enlightened 
common  sense,  and  to  point  out  a  striking  fact  of  our  daily 
experience.  Observing  the  material  world  about  us,  we  see 
groups  of  bodies  which  are  endowed  with  characteristics 
which  are  found  in  them,  and  them  only,  and  which  are 
sharply  marked  off  one  from  another.  Thus  living  things, 
with  their  powers  of  growth  and  nutrition,  animals,  with 
their  characteristics  of  sense  and  intelligence,  men,  with 
their  mark  of  reason,  are  striking  examples  of  such  groups. 
Now  it  is  impossible  that  this  distribution  of  characteristics 
should  be  accidental  or  arbitrary,  for  unless  there  were  some 
essential  connection  between  them,  and  the  natures  of  the 
things,  we  should  sometimes  come  across  a  member  of  one 
group  which  possessed  the  characteristics  of  another,  e.g.  a 
stone  which  was  able  to  feed  itself  and  grow.  This  we  never 
do,  however,  so  that  we  may  conclude  that  these  character- 
istics spring  from  the  natures  of  the  things  themselves,  or 
are,  what  the  the  Scholastics  call,  their  properties,  and  since 
they  are  distinct  from  one  another,  so  also  will  be  the  natures 
which  give  rise  to  them. 

These  simple  considerations  at  least  suffice  to  show  that 
there  is  a  prima  facie  presumption  that  the  world  is  not  as 
simple  as  Materialistic  Monism  would  have  us  believe  ;  and 
we  can  thus  turn  to  a  more  detailed  consideration  of  the 
various  theories  which  have  been  advanced  as  to  its 
composition,  and  the  constitution  of  matter. 


CHAPTER   I 

MECHANISM 
History  of  the  Theory — Its  Essential  Character — Criticism. 

The  first  of  the  theories  with  regard  to  the  constitution  of 
matter  to  engage  our  attention  is  that  generally  known  as 
Mechanism.  In  scholastic  text-books  it  is  more  usually 
called  Atomism,  but  since  this  term  is  ambiguous,  for  it 
might  be  supposed  to  apply  to  the  Atomic  Theory,  and  the 
scientific  doctrine  of  atoms,  it  is  better  to  relinquish  it  and 
use  the  philosophically  more  appropriate  name  of  Mechan- 
ism ;  of  which  the  distinctive  feature  is  the  denial  of  specific 
differences,  or  differences  of  nature,  between  bodies. 

The  origins  of  all  Atomic  and  Mechanistic  theories  are  to 
be  found  in  Leucippus  and  Democritus.  In  their  view,  the 
question  of  the  divisibility  of  matter  is  regarded  as  of  capital 
importance.  Extended  concrete  substance  cannot,  it  is  con- 
tended, be  infinitely  divisible.  What,  then,  remains  when 
it  is  divided  as  far  as  possible  ?  Not  unextended  points,  for 
then  the  extended  would  be  composed  of  the  unextended  : 
nor  yet  nothing  at  all,  for  then  bodies  would  be  mere  appear- 
ances. Therefore,  there  must  remain  some  extended  and 
indivisible  particles,  which  particles  are  called  atoms.  The 
existence,  however,  of  atoms  is  not  the  distinguishing 
characteristic  of  the  atomic  theories  ;  this  consists  in  the 
denial  that  the  atoms  differ  from  one  another  in  kind,  or  if 
there  exist  different  species  of  atoms,  at  least  they  do  not 
gain  or  lose  anything  in  combination,  but  the  mere  fact  of 
their  conjunction  and  consequent  interaction  produces  an 
apparent  transformation  in  the  composite  bodies,  as  com- 
pared with  the  simple  atoms.  The  theory  accounted  for 
everything  in  the  world,  including  force  and  intelligence,  as 

25 


26  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

the  product  of  extension  and  the  passive  movement  of  the 
atoms.  Such  a  theory  rules  out  all  purpose  which,  as  we 
shall  see,  is  so  marked  a  feature  of  Aristotle's  view  of  nature  ; 
and,  moreover,  avoids  the  dualism  of  mind  and  matter,  since 
it  is  purely  materialistic.  It  was  developed  with  this  object 
in  view  by  Epicurus,  and  revived  in  the  first  century  B.C.  by 
Lucretius,  who  shared  with  Epicurus  the  desire  to  banish 
superstitious  fear  of  the  gods,  and  their  action  on  the  world 
from  men's  minds.  After  this  time,  however,  such  material- 
istic theories  practically  disappeared  from  philosophic 
thought  under  the  influence  of  Aristoteleanism,  and  we  do 
not  find  any  recrudescence  of  them  till  the  fifteenth  century, 
when  they  again  arose  in  connection  with  the  metaphysical 
speculations  of  Nicholas  of  Cusa  (1401-1464)  and  others.  It 
was,  however,  the  theories  of  Giordano  Bruno,  in  the  next 
century,  which  had  the  most  important  influence  on  the 
later  developments  of  philosophical  atomism  ;  and  which 
may  be  taken  as  the  connecting  link  between  the  ancient 
mechanistic  theories  and  the  modern. 

This  modern  period  opens  with  the  purely  mechanistic 
physics  of  Descartes  (1596-1650)  and  Gassendi  (1592-1655), 
and  with  it  the  reaction  against  the  Aristotelean  cosmology 
comes  to  a  head.  According  to  Descartes  all  physical  pheno- 
mena are  to  be  traced  to  extension  and  motion,  the  nature 
of  body  being  identified  by  him  with  spatial  extension.  He 
was  not,  however,  an  Atomist  in  the  same  sense  as  Demo- 
critus,  for  he  regarded  all  space  as  one  fundamental  substance 
which  is  infinitely  divisible.  If,  then,  body  and  extension  are 
identical,  there  will  be  no  vacua  within  the  material  universe, 
since  these  would  be  extended,  and  so  be  body,  not  vacuum  : 
and,  moreover,  the  material  universe  must  itself  be  infinite, 
since,  if  it  were  finite,  there  would  be  a  vacuum  outside  it, 
which  would,  in  its  turn,  be  extended,  and  so  a  body,  thus 
forming  part  of  the  material  universe.  Further,  if  we  are  to 
have  an  absolute  plenum,  all  movement  must  be  rotatory, 
otherwise  there  would  be  a  diminution  of  material  substance 
in  one  place,  and  an  increase  in  another.  In  this  rotatory 
motion  particles  become  rounded,  and  so  produce  three 
elements,  elementary  fire,  air,  and  earth  from  which  the 


MECHANISM  27 

different  parts  of  the  universe  are  derived.  Gassendi,  a 
contemporary  of  Descartes,  had,  meanwhile,  returned  to  the 
theory  of  the  ancients  with  regard  to  the  atomic  structure 
of  the  world.  In  his  view,  the  only  principles  in  nature  are 
empty  space  and  atoms,  the  latter  being  composed  of  one 
and  the  same  substance,  and  distinguished  only  by  differ- 
ences of  magnitude,  shape,  and  weight.  He  found  the 
explanation  of  all  the  physical  properties  of  bodies  in  the 
motion  of  the  atoms.  The  English  philosopher,  Thomas 
Hobbes,  another  contemporary  of  Descartes,  expressed 
similar  views. 

These  general  mechanistic  theories  were  greatly  strength- 
ened by  the  practical  experiments  of  Robert  Boyle  (1626- 
1691),  on  the  basis  of  which  he  attempted  to  explain  all 
chemical  changes  mechanically.  He  insisted  on  the  quanti- 
tative determination  of  weights,  thus  preparing  the  way  for 
the  modern  chemical  theory  of  elements,  since  he  recognised 
specific  weight  and  chemical  reaction  as  the  distinguishing 
marks  of  any  particular  substance. 

It  is  obvious  that  the  main  purpose  of  all  these  mechanistic 
theories  is  to  simplify  our  ideas  of  matter,  by  accounting  for 
everything  by  means  of  indestructible  material  units  which 
are  all  of  the  same  kind,  and  local  motion  communicated  by 
impact,  thus  rendering  obsolete  all  discussion  as  to  the 
natures  and  qualities  of  particular  bodies.  The  idea  of  a 
body  exerting  some  active  force  of  its  own  cannot  be  em- 
braced in  such  a  scheme  ;  both  because  force  cannot  be 
regarded  as  corpuscular,  and  because  it  is,  moreover,  a 
qualitative,  rather  than  a  quantitative,  conception.  New- 
ton's discovery  of  the  law  of  gravitation  necessarily  led, 
however,  to  the  idea  that  the  atoms  exert  an  attractive  force 
on  one  another  at  a  distance  ;  and  though  this  notion  was 
resolutely  opposed  both  by  Newton  himself  and  many  others, 
it  came  gradually  to  be  accepted,  and  the  simple  picture  of 
the  great  world-machine  painted  by  the  earlier  Atomists  was 
destroyed.  It  would,  nevertheless,  be  a  mistake  to  suppose 
that  the  mechanical  view  of  nature,  according  to  which  all 
material  happenings  are  ruled  by  a  strict  mathematical 
necessity,  perished  along  with  it ;  for  though  the  conception 


28  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

of  force  is  not  amenable  to  mathematical  treatment,  its 
effects  can  be  quantitatively  expressed  ;  and  thus  a  mechan- 
ical theory,  modified  by  the  introduction  of  dynamical  con- 
ceptions, for  long  continued  to  hold,  and  probably  still  does 
hold,  the  field,  as  the  orthodox  philosophy  of  matter, 
especially  among  scientists.  The  theory  so  modified  will  be 
considered  in  the  next  chapter. 

Reduced  to  their  simplest  form  the  earlier  mechanical 
theories  are  seen  to  consist  of  two  propositions  : 

i.  All  bodies  are  composed  of  material  elements  of 
essentially  the  same  kind — matter  is  homogeneous. 

2.  All  corporeal  properties  can  be  explained  by  local 
motion  which  is  governed  by  mechanical  laws. 

When  stated  in  this  way  the  theories  are  evidently  open 
to  the  objections  urged  against  Monism  in  general,  for  we 
find,  both  in  the  organic  and  in  the  inorganic  world,  a  variety 
of  constant  and  stable  types  of  bodies.  We  see  bodies  which 
are  distinguished  from  one  another  by  definite  and  unchang- 
ing characteristics  :  so  bodies  are  by  nature  liquids,  solids, 
and  gases,  under  determinate,  but  different,  conditions. 
They  have  differing  though  constant  weights,  as,  for  example, 
zinc  is  lighter  than  lead.  These  weights  are  also  known 
scientifically  to  be  constant  and  different  for  each  one  of  the 
chemical  elements.  Further,  the  boiling  and  freezing  points 
of  the  different  elements  exhibit  a  constant  difference.  Such 
differences,  therefore,  cannot  arise  from  the  circumstances 
in  which  the  bodies  are  placed,  but  must  belong  to  them  by 
nature,  and  be  their  properties,  so  that  to  deny  difference 
of  nature,  or  specific  differences,  is  to  make  these  bodies 
inexplicable. 

The  second  dogma  of  mechanism  is  that  all  the  apparent 
changes  of  bodies,  and  all  corporeal  phenomena,  are  to  be 
explained  by  the  local  movement  of  the  atoms.  Now,  such 
local  motion  alone  cannot  be  a  sufficient  explanation  of  the 
phenomena,  since  one  of  the  most  striking  of  these  is  the 
activity  or  force  of  bodies.  Local  motion,  however,  is  a 
result  of  activity,  and  so  cannot  be  its  cause  or  explanation.1 
Moreover,  local  motion,  as  such,  cannot  be  communicated 

1  Cf.  Nys,  Cosmologie,  Vol.  I,  Sec.  125.    (Louvain,  1928.) 


MECHANISM  29 

from  one  body  to  another,  for,  as  M.  Meyerson  says  :  '  There 
can  be  no  movement  without  a  substantial  substratum, 
without  something  which  moves.  Movement  is  in  no  sense  a 
substance,  the  most  that  we  can  do  is  to  consider  it  as  a 
state.  Supposing  we  accept  this  latter  notion,  and  consider 
that  this  state  must  last  indefinitely,  as  the  principle  of 
inertia  requires,  how  can  it  break  away  from  one  body  to 
attach  itself  to  another  ?  It  would  be  necessary,  as  Lotze 
has  very  rightly  remarked,  that  this  state  should  exist  of 
itself,  between  the  two,  for  a  moment,  even  if  this  moment 
be  infinitely  short,  becoming  thus  a  true  substance,  which  is 
absurd.  It  is  consequently  quite  impossible  to  conceive  of 
the  transmission  of  movement  from  atom  to  atom  without 
the  intervention  of  a  special  faculty,  a  mysterious  agent.'1 
So  it  would  be  like  the  grin  of  the  Cheshire  cat — a  grin 
without  a  cat. 

Lastly,  as  a  philosophical  theory,  mechanism  is  inaccept- 
able,  since  it  does  not  go  to  the  root  of  the  matter  ;  for,  in 
fact,  it  does  not  explain  the  constitution  of  either  simple  or 
compound  bodies  :  not  of  simple  bodies,  since  these  are  the 
atoms  themselves,  and  no  attempt  is  made  to  explain  the 
atom  :  nor  of  compound  bodies,  which  are  homogeneous, 
having  different  properties  from  their  elements,  as  water 
has  different  properties  from  those  of  oxygen  and  hydrogen. 
Neither  of  these  facts  is  explained  by  Mechanism,  since  from 
the  atoms,  as  conceived  of  by  the  Mechanists,  there  cannot 
arise  a  homogeneous  compound,  for  they  are  complete  in 
themselves,  and  combine  by  mere  juxtaposition,  remaining, 
in  themselves,  the  same.  Nor  can  a  mere  juxtaposition  of 
the  elements  give  rise  to  entirely  new  properties,  but  will 
only  give  the  sum  of  the  properties  already  existing  in  the 
elements.2 

1  E.  Meyerson,  IdentiU  et  Realite  (1912),  p.  332. 
*  Cf.  Nys,  op.  cit.,  Sect.  78-88. 


CHAPTER  II 

DYNAMISM 
Its  Nature — Theories  of  Leibniz,  Boscovich  and  Kant — Criticism. 

Since  our  concern  is  only  with  philosophical  theories  as  to 
the  nature  of  matter,  we  can  omit  any  consideration  of  the 
various  modifications  which  have  been  imported  into 
Cartesian  Mechanism,  considered  purely  as  a  physical 
theory  ;  and  turn  our  attention  to  the  group  of  philosophical 
theories  which  are  often  generically  known  as  Dynamism. 
The  characteristic  tenets  of  this  school  are  : 

1.  The  assertion  of  the  essential  activity  of  material 
substance,  and  indeed  of  all  substance. 

2.  The  denial  of  extension  to  the  basic  principles  of  bodies. 

3.  The  consequent  assertion  that  all  bodies,  and  all  cor- 
poreal phenomena,  are  produced  by  the  grouping  and  inter- 
play of  simple  unextended  forces. 

In  virtue  of  this  last  view,  Dynamism  joins  hands  with 
Mechanism  in  holding  that  bodies  are  merely  aggregates  of 
elements  which  are  in  themselves  simple,  i.e.  not  having 
parts  of  different  kinds,  and  which  do  not  change  intrin- 
sically in  combination.  In  all  other  respects,  however, 
Dynamism  is  the  opposing  extreme  to  Mechanism,  since,  for 
the  former,  the  basic  principles  of  the  material  world  are 
active  forces  which  have  no  extension,  while  for  Mechanism 
extension  is  the  very  essence  of  body,  and  force,  which  is 
variable,  active,  and  tending  to  definite  ends,  is  incompatible 
with  the  tenet  that  all  change  arises  from  local  motion  only. 

The  initiator  of  Dynamism  is  generally  acknowledged  to 
have  been  Leibniz  (1646-1716).1 

He  was  first  '  charmed  '  by  the  mechanical  explanation  of 

1  Though  Fr.  Hoenen,  S.J.,  thinks  that  Dynamism  should  not  be 
attributed  to  him.    Hoenen,  Cosmologia,  p.  414. 

30 


DYNAMISM  31 

the  world,  but  soon  came  to  see  '  that  the  notion  of  extended 
mass  taken  alone  is  insufficient,  we  must  also  employ  the 
notion  of  force,  a  very  intelligible  notion,  though  its  source 
may  be  metaphysical.'1  Thus  he  came  to  abolish  extension 
and  matter  altogether  out  of  reality.  So,  in  opposition  to 
the  ideas  of  Descartes,  who  considered  the  constituent  of 
body  to  be  something  passive,  viz.  extension,  he  maintained 
that  body  is  essentially  active.  From  the  principle  '  that 
which  does  not  act  does  not  deserve  the  name  of  substance  ' 
he  soon  passed  to  the  statement  that  active  force  is  the  very 
essence  of  material  beings.  He  thus  spiritualised  matter, 
and  decomposed  it  into  an  infinite  number  of  infinitesimally 
small  '  bodies '  or  elements,  which  are  unextended  and 
simple,  i.e.  without  parts.  These  he  called  Monads.  They 
are  essentially  active,  and,  in  fact,  always  in  action  :  they 
can,  however,  only  act  internally,  not  on  one  another,  or  on 
anything  outside  themselves,  since  otherwise  they  would  not 
be  simple.2  He  expressed  this  in  the  saying  :  '  The  monads 
have  no  windows  by  which  anything  can  enter  or  go  out.' 
Every  being  is  composed  of  a  whole  world  of  these  little 
'  souls  ' :  'A  world  of  creatures,  living  beings,  animals, 
entelechies,  souls,  exists  in  the  minutest  part  of  matter. 
Each  portion  of  matter  may  be  conceived  as  a  garden  full  of 
plants  or  as  a  pond  full  of  fish.  But  every  branch  of  a  plant, 
every  limb  of  an  animal,  and  every  drop  of  the  fluids  within 
it,  is  also  such  a  garden,  such  a  pond.  .  .  .  Thus  there  is 
nothing  arid,  sterile  or  dead  in  the  universe.'3  But  since 
the  Monads  are  simple  and  unextended,  it  seems  impossible 
to  explain  extension  and  movement  by  their  means.  Hence 
Leibniz  denies  the  reality  of  these  ;  they  are  appearances. 
Thus  in  perception  we  produce  the  appearances  of  things 
which  we  represent  as  outside  one  another.  For  this 
representation  we  have  need  to  construct  the  fiction  of 
extension  ;  so  that  extension  is  not  what  we  perceive,  it  is  the 
background  which  we  construct  in  order  to  represent  indivi- 
duals as  outside  one  another.    '  It  is  the  artifice  by  which  in 

1  Leibniz,  Art.  in  Le  Journal  des  Savants  (1695),  quoted  by  Wildon 
Carr.    Leibniz,  p.  78.     (Benn,  Leaders  of  Philosophy  Series.) 

2  Leibniz,  Monadology,  No.  7.  *  Ibid.,  Nos.  67,  69. 


32  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

perceiving  a  multitude  of  distinct  individuals  we  represent 
their  togetherness.'1  It  is  clear,  however,  that  the  Monads 
act  harmoniously  in  concord,  as  if,  in  fact,  they  acted  on  one 
another  ;  so  the  earth,  air,  water,  etc.,  all  appear  to  contri- 
bute to  the  growth  of  a  plant,  and  the  plant  to  grow  con- 
tinuously and  harmoniously  :  and  the  same  is  true  of  the 
working  of  the  universe  as  a  whole.  If,  then,  the  Monads  do 
not,  in  fact,  interact,  how  is  this  harmony  and  apparent 
efficient  causality  to  be  accounted  for  ?  Not  being  connected 
intrinsically  they  must  be  held  together  extrinsically  by  a  pre- 
established  harmony,  which  God,  the  supreme  Monad,  had 
imposed  on  the  universe  at  its  creation,  so  that  the  Monads 
all  developin  concord  and  give  the  appearance  of  mutual 
help  and  dependence.  As  if  we  had  a  number  of  clocks  all 
striking  in  turn  it  might  be  thought  that  each  set  the  next 
one  on,  though,  in  fact,  their  striking  has  been  arranged  to 
occur  in  this  order  ;  in  either  case  we  should  have  a  series  of 
chimes  such  as  that  in  '  La  Boutique  Fantasque.' 

A  somewhat  similar  theory  was  proposed  in  the  middle  of 
the  eighteenth  century  by  the  Jesuit,  Boscovich.  This  very 
remarkable  man  was  rather  a  scientist  and  mathematician 
than  a  philosopher,  and  his  system  is  less  complete  from  a 
philosophical  point  of  view  than  that  of  Leibniz.  According 
to  him  matter  consists  of  a  swarm  of  atoms,  each  of  which 
occupies  a  geometrical  point  of  space,  is  capable  of  motion, 
and  possesses  a  certain  mass,  so  that  a  definite  force  is 
required  that  each  atom  may  acquire  a  given  acceleration. 
The  atoms  attract  one  another,  if  separated  by  anything 
more  than  a  small  distance,  with  a  force  varying  inversely 
as  the  square  of  the  distance  between  them.  At  small  dis- 
tances, the  force  is  supposed  to  be  alternately  attractive  and 
repulsive  ;  and  in  order  to  avoid  the  difficulty  of  two  atoms 
coalescing  in  the  same  place,  Boscovich  imagines  that  for  all 
distances  below  a  certain  minimum  the  force  is  repulsive, 
and  increases  indefinitely  in  proportion  as  the  distance 
diminishes.  Thus,  all  actions  are  actions  at  a  distance,  and 
there  is  no  such  thing  as  actual  contact.    It  was  the  idea  that 

1  Wildon  Carr,  Leibniz,  p.  91.  Leaders  of  Philosophy  Series.  (Benn, 
1929.) 


DYNAMISM  33 

the  atoms  act  thus  at  a  distance  which  led  him  to  abandon 
the  notion  that  they  are  extended,  since,  without  contact, 
the  conception  of  extension  seemed  unnecessary  :  and  this 
view  was  continued  by  Ampere  and  Faraday,  who  regarded 
the  atoms  as  unextended,  or  simple  centres  of  force.  Here 
we  see  clearly  that  the  scheme  put  forward  by  Boscovich 
was  rather  a  scientific  hypothesis  than  a  philosophical  theory. 

The  theory  of  Kant  is  akin  to  these,  but  differs  from  them 
in  two  respects  :  (i)  In  accordance  with  his  general  prin- 
ciples, he  does  not  allow  that  we  can  know  what  are  the 
constituents  of  bodies  in  themselves,  but  only  as  they  are 
conceived  of  by  us  ;  and  (2)  he  will  not  admit  the  possibility 
of  a  vacuum.  As  conceived  of,  then,  body,  according  to 
Kant,  is  something  mobile  which  fills  a  space  ;  and  this 
filling  of  space  implies  a  resistance  to  anything  which  would 
penetrate  into  this  space.  Now,  since  all  resistance  pre- 
supposes a  force  of  resistance,  and  all  motion  a  force  which 
moves,  body  can  only  fill  a  space  by  means  of  a  motive  force, 
which  must  consist  in  a  kind  of  elasticity,  and  which  Kant 
calls  a  force  of  expansion  and  concentration.  It  is  these 
plastic  forces  which  constitute  bodies  as  conceived  of  by  us. 

The  views  on  the  constitution  of  bodies  held  by  various 
schools  may  be  exhibited  in  the  following  scheme  : 

Bodies  are  composed  according  to  : 

S.  Thomas 
of    two    elements :    one    potentially    extended,    and    one 

unextended 


Mechanists  Dynamists 

of  one  extended  element         of  one  unextended  element 

Kant 

I 
two  elements  in  idea. 


34  MODERN   THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

So  S.  Thomas  combines  mechanism  and  dynamism  in  a 
positive  synthesis  :   Kant  in  a  negative  one. 

Criticism  of  Dynamism  in  General. 

i.  There  can  be  no  doubt  that  bodies  appear  to  us  to  be 
extended,  and  any  theory  which  is  to  claim  to  be  satisfactory, 
must  take  account  this  fact,  and  offer  some  explana- 
tion of  it,  either  by  allowing  that  they  really  are  so,  or  if  it 
denies  this,  by  advancing  some  feasible  reason  to  account 
for  their  appearing  to  be  so.  The  first  course  is  not  open  to 
the  Dynamists,  and  they  cannot  offer  a  satisfactory  explana- 
tion of  the  appearance,  which  will  be  in  accord  with  their 
notions  as  to  the  nature  of  bodies  ;  for  their  appearance  of 
extension  must  have  some  cause.  Now  this  cause  cannot  be 
the  senses  themselves,  since,  on  the  Dynamist  hypothesis, 
these  are  also  unextended,  and  so  contain  nothing  which 
would  cause  their  objects  to  appear  as  extended.  Nor  can 
the  cause  of  this  appearance  be  external  agents,  since  these 
also  labour  under  the  same  disadvantage  :  in  a  word,  since, 
according  to  the  Dynamists,  there  is  nothing  in  the  universe 
which  is  extended,  there  is  equally  nothing  in  the  universe 
which  could  be  the  cause  of  an  extended  appearance.  Leib- 
niz's suggestion  that  we  produce  it  in  order  to  represent  a 
numberof  distinct  things  together  is  clearly  untrue,  since 
the  notion  of  distinction  and  external  position  are  quite 
different,  that  of  distinction  being  wider  ;  and,  moreover, 
we  do  not  always  represent  distinct  things  as  outside  one 
another  in  space  as,  for  example,  a  series  of  numbers,  or  our 
various  thoughts  and  desires,  or  immaterial  beings,  such  as 
angels,  or  even  God  and  the  material  world. 

2.  According  to  Dynamism,  matter  is  composed  of  simple 
forces.  Now  these  forces  must  be  either  in  contact  or  not  in 
contact.  If  they  are  not  in  contact  they  will  coalesce,  form- 
ing one  force  at  a  geometrical  point,  as  Boscovich  rightly 
observed.  For  it  is  clear  that  a  certain  extension  is  required 
for  contact :  if  a  tangent  of  a  circle  touched  it  at  one  point 
only,  it  would  not  touch  it  at  all.  In  this  case  the  plurality 
of  bodies  would  disappear.  If,  on  the  other  hand,  they  are 
not  in  contact ;  in  any  one  body,  the  many  monads  or  forces 


DYNAMISM  35 

which  compose  it  will  be  entirely  distinct  one  from  another, 
as  regards  their  entity,  even  though  they  be  supposed  to  act 
on  one  another  across  a  vacuum.  Hence  the  unity  of  such  a 
body  will  be  wholly  destroyed.  This  is  also  true  if  they  are 
supposed  to  coalesce  in  a  point,  since  this  point,  which  will 
be  the  only  body,  and  therefore  the  only  unified  body,  will 
be  composed  of  a  multitude  of  forces  which  will  preserve 
their  own  entity  in  it.  In  either  case,  therefore,  it  is  imposs- 
ible to  maintain  the  unity  of  bodies,  on  the  Dynamist 
hypothesis.  Now,  not  only  is  this  result  in  direct  contradic- 
tion with  experience  but,  if  no  body  is  a  unity,  we  can  gain 
no  notion  of  the  nature  of  any  body,  since  it  will  not  have 
one  ;  and  a  fortiori  shall  be  unable  to  determine  the  nature  of 
body  in  general,  but  shall  say  it  is  force,  which  will  be  a  term 
without  any  one  meaning,  and  so  a  mere  word  to  cover  our 
ignorance. 


CHAPTER  III 

THE  THOMISTIC  THEORY  OF  THE  NATURE  OF  MATTER 

Nature  and  Data  of  Question — History  and  Explanation  of  Hylo- 
morphism — The  Reasons  Advanced  to  Support  it — Additional 
Explanations  of  the  Meaning  of  '  Matter  '  and  '  Form ' — Some 
Difficulties  Considered. 

The  problem  of  which  we  are  to  attempt  to  find  the  solution 
is  :  what,  in  the  last  resort,  is  the  nature  of  matter  or  of 
bodies  ?  Not  of  this  or  that  body,  but  of  material  things  in 
general ;  nor  yet  of  what  chemical  elements  bodies  may  be 
composed,  for  even  if  we  were  successful  in  showing  that  all 
bodies  were  compounds  of  one  element,  such  as  hydrogen,  or 
one  force,  such  as  electricity,  as  has  been  sometimes  suggested, 
the  question  would  still  remain  what  is  the  nature  of  hydro- 
gen and  electricity,  and  we  should  have  our  original  problem 
still  on  our  hands.  The  question,  therefore,  is  not  a  physical 
one  merely,  but  both  physical  and  metaphysical.  It  is 
physical,  since  the  starting  point  of  our  enquiry  must  be  the 
properties  and  behaviour  of  bodies  as  made  known  to  us  by 
common  and  scientific  observation.  The  experimental  or 
empirical  investigation  of  material  phenomena  is  the  work 
of  the  physicist  :  and  we  could  take  his  results  as  they  stand 
as  the  basis  of  our  investigation,  were  it  not  that,  unfortun- 
ately, he  often  imports  theories  of  a  philosophical  kind  into 
them.  Moreover,  as  we  shall  see  later,  there  is  much  dis- 
agreement among  scientists,  and,  what  is  worse,  undoubted 
error  in  the  views  of  some  of  them,  as  to  the  nature  of  scien- 
tific investigation.  For  it  should  be  observed  at  the  start 
that  it  is  impossible  for  the  scientist,  as  for  the  philosopher, 
to  deal  with  '  brute  fact,'  i.e.  mere  disconnected  happenings 
in  the  material  world  :  he  is  bound  to  connect  them  by  a 
meaning  of  some  kind,  bringing  them  all  under  a  general 

36 


THOMISTIC  THEORY   OF   MATTER  37 

law,  and  it  is  here  that  exaggerations  and  aberrations  are 
apt  to  creep  in.  So  Newton  observed  the  movements  of 
bodies,  and  from  a  mass  of  observations  concluded  to  the 
general  law  that  they  move  as  if  actuated  by  a  pull  which  is 
directly  proportionate  to  their  masses  and  inversely  to  the 
square  of  the  distance  between  them.  It  was  an  easy  jump, 
then,  to  stating  that  they  were  attracted,  or  pulled  together, 
by  a  force  of  this  kind  ;  though  such  a  transition  from 
observation  to  theory  was,  strictly  speaking,  more  than  the 
facts  warranted.  It  follows  that  it  is  not  possible  for  the 
philosopher  to  assume  that  physical  laws  and  theories,  as 
enunciated  by  scientists  at  any  particular  epoch,  are  philo- 
sophically true  ;  but  in  his  enquiry  he  will  take  as  the  basis 
of  his  investigation  the  best  knowledge  available  about  the 
material  world  ;  and  this  will  include  both  the  knowledge 
obtained  by  common  observation  and  that  gained  by  scien- 
tific enquiry,  the  latter  being  accepted  by  the  philosopher 
only  provisionally,  and  under  certain  conditions.  For  it  is 
to  be  noticed  that  scientific  knowledge  must  always  be  an 
extension  of,  and  dependent  on,  common  observation,  for 
though  the  scientist,  by  reason  of  the  refinement  of  his 
instruments,  may  be  able  to  extend  the  latter,  he  must  in 
the  last  resort  rely  on  his  five  senses  and  intellect  in  using 
them  ;  so  that  the  philosopher  could  not  accept  from  the 
scientist  a  law  or  theory  which  is  in  contradiction  with  the 
evidence  of  the  senses.  It  is  clear,  therefore,  that  this 
enquiry  has  a  metaphysical  as  well  as  a  physical  side.  It 
must  check  the  empirical  observations  of  the  scientist,  and 
of  the  senses,  by  considerations  of  a  purely  intellectual 
character,  for  the  object  in  view  is  not  merely  to  investigate 
the  phenomena,  i.e.  those  things  which  can  be  known  by  the 
senses,  but  something  which  is  outside  the  sphere  of  pheno- 
mena or  appearances,  viz.  the  very  nature  of  things  which  so 
appear,  and  this  is  knowable  only  by  the  intellect.  Thus 
any  theory  as  to  the  essential  constituents  of  bodies  must 
satisfy  four  general  conditions  : 

1.  It  must  explain  the  inner  nature  of  all  bodies. 

2.  It  must  explain  not  only  the  unity,  but  also  the  essential 
diversity  of  bodies. 


38  MODERN   THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

3.  It  must  explain  the  dualism  of  bodies  :  why  they  are 
both  active  and  passive,  changing  and  unchanging  (their 
stability),  one  and  multiple,  alike  and  different. 

4.  It  must  take  its  rise  from,  and  be  in  full  accordance 
with  ascertained  facts  obtained  by  observation. 

The  Thomistic  answer  to  the  question  :  what  are  the 
essential  constituents' of  bodies,  can  be  summed  up  in  three 
statements  : 

1.  There  is  in  bodies  a  substantial  material  principle,  and 
substantial  formal  principle. 

2.  Both  these  principles  are  incomplete  substances. 

3.  The  material  principle  has  the  same  relation  to  the 
formal  as  potentiality  to  actuality. 

What  is  meant  by  material  and  formal  principles,  or 
matter  and  form  can  be  seen  roughly  by  means  of  an  example: 
the  flour,  raisins,  eggs,  etc.,  are  the  material  principles  of  the 
plum  pudding,  but  these  have  to  be  combined  in  the  proper 
proportions,  mixed  and  boiled  in  a  certain  way  in  order  to 
obtain  a  plum  pudding.  The  result  of  such  combination, 
mixing,  etc.,  is  the  formal  principle  of  the  pudding,  making  it 
a  Plum  Pudding,  differing  from  all  other  kinds  of  pudding. 
Similarly  at  the  start  we  may  take  an  example  to  illustrate 
what  is  meant  by  potentiality  and  actuality  ;  as  when  we 
say  :  '  John  can  read,'  i.e.  has  the  capacity  or  potentiality  of 
reading,  and  '  John  is  reading,'  i.e.  is  in  the  act  of  reading,  is 
reading  actually.  We  shall  shortly  see  the  meanings  of  these 
terms  more  scientifically  and  precisely  ;  but  before  we  do 
this,  and  pass  to  the  proof  of  the  Thomistic  theory,  it  will  be 
useful  to  glance  at  its  origin  and  history. 

The  History  of  the  Theory  of  Matter  and  Form. 

Matter.  The  theory  of  matter  and  form,  or,  as  it  is  often 
called,  Hylomorphism,  is  due  to  Aristotle.  It  is  true  that 
Plato  had  already  introduced  a  notion  from  which  that  of 
matter  was  derived,  in  the  Timaeus,  viz.  that  of  Xu>pa  or 
'  space.'  This  is  conceived  of  by  him  as  the  screen  on  which 
the  images  of  the  Ideas  or  Forms  are  thrown.  In  itself  it  has 
no  form,  no  determination,  no  features  of  any  kind.  It  is 
not  empty  space,  nor  yet  in  any  way  the  single  underlying 


THOMISTIC  THEORY   OF  MATTER  39 

substance  of  the  universe,  it  is  the  reality  on  which  the 
appearances  show,  its  sole  attribute  being  to  support  them. 
Since  Plato  affirms  that  the  Forms  alone  are  real,  he  must 
consequently  deny  reality  to  this  background  of  appearances, 
and  so  he  sometimes  calls  it  '  nothing,'  tu  p)  6V,  inasmuch 
as  it  is  altogether  other  than  the  forms.  But  since  it  also  in 
some  way  exists,  it  is  a  nothing  or  not-being,  which,  in  some 
way,  is.  It  is  thought  of  as  being  in  existence  prior,  with  at 
least  a  logical  priority,  to  its  determination  by  the  impress  of 
the  Forms  ;  and  so  may  perhaps  be  compared  to  the  chaos 
of  Genesis,  which  is  itself  something,  prior  to  the  possession 
of  any  definite  nature.  This  obscure  being,  though  far  enough 
removed  in  some  respects  from  Aristotle's  '  matter  '  ;  since  it 
is  altogether  immovable  and  unchangeable,  and  contrasted 
with  reality  which  is  Form  only  ;  is  nevertheless  in  other 
ways  akin  to  it,  in  so  far  as  it  suggests  the  root  idea  which 
underlies  the  Aristotelean  '  matter,'  of  a  not-being  which  in 
some  way  is.1  So  long  as  this  entity  is  thought  of  as  '  other 
than  '  reality,  no  intelligible  meaning  can  be  attached  to  this 
phrase  ;  and  Aristotle  working  on  the  Platonic  notions  insists 
that  it  too  must  be  real,  though  formless.  Though  it  can 
have  no  existence  of  its  own,  yet  where  it  exists  owing  to 
form  being  joined  with  it,  it  is  not  identified  with  form,  but 
has  its  own  reality.  For  reality  and  existence,  though  com- 
monly confused,  are,  as  we  shall  see,  two  very  different 
things.  Aristotle  therefore  defines  it  in  two  ways  :  positively 
and  negatively.  The  positive  definition,  given  in  the 
Physics  (io,2a3i),  is  :  matter  is  the  first  subject  of  each  thing, 
from  which,  since  it  is  intrinsic,  something  which  is  not  per 
accidens  comes  into  being. 

By  the  word  first,  it  is  differentiated  from  second  matter, 
which  is  what  we  ordinarily  mean  in  English  when  we  speak  of 
matter,  for  this,  though  the  subject  of  accidents,  is  yet  not  the 
first  subject,  since  there  must  have  been  a  prior  subject  of  the 
substantial  nature  :  e.g.  cloth  can  be  neither  white  nor  black, 
till  the  nature  of  cloth  has  been  embodied  in  matter.  Cloth 
in  the  abstract  is  of  no  colour. 

The  words  '  being  intrinsic  '  show  that  it  is  not  privation, 

1  Cf.  R.  P.  Omez,  O.P.,  La  Notion  de  x^Pa-  Revue  des  Sciences  Philo- 
sophiques  et  Theologiques  (1925),  pp.  433  ff.    Taylor,  A.  E.,  Plato,  pp.  456  ff. 


40  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

but  a  positive  principle  which  enters  into  the  composition 
of  the  complete  being. 

Lastly,  the  phrase  '  something  which  is  not  per  accidens 
comes  into  being  '  indicates  that  the  compound  of  matter  and 
form  is  not  an  accidental,  but  a  substantial  unity,  the  two 
together  making  up  a  complete  nature,  and  being  joined  in 
one  nature  ;  not  as  in  the  case  of  an  accidental  union  each 
retaining  as  its  own  nature,  as,  e.g.  glass  and  water  in  the 
case  of  a  glass  of  water.  The  second  and  negative  definition 
which  he  gives  is  :  '  By  matter  I  mean  that  which  in  itself 
is  neither  a  particular  thing,  nor  of  a  certain  quantity,  nor 
assigned  to  any  other  of  the  categories  by  which  being 
is  determined.'  (VII  Met.,  i02o,a20.)  This  definition  has 
received  a  traditional  Latin  form  as :  materia  prima  secundum 
seipsam  non  est  quid,  neque  quale,  neque  quantum,  neque 
aliquid  eorum  quibus  ens  determinatur. 

It  is  not  any  particular  thing,  for  in  this  case  it  would  be  a 
specifically  complete  substance  ;  nor  is  it  in  any  of  the 
categories,  since  all  presuppose  a  pre-existing  substance, 
while  matter  is  absolutely  first  as  a  subject.  Yet,  though  it  is 
not  in  any  of  the  categories  (i.e.  the  general  classes  into 
which  things  can  be  divided)  directly,  it  is  reducible  to 
that  of  substance. 

.  First  matter  must  therefore  be  carefully  distinguished 
frorn  what  is  commonly  called  matter,  and  which  the 
Scholastics  name  Second  Matter  ;  since  first  matter  is  incom- 
plete in  itself,  and  cannot  be  known  in  itself,  or  by  the 
senses.  It  can  only  be  known  indirectly,  by  means  of  form, 
and  cannot  be  touched,  seen,  or  smelt,  being  something  dis- 
coverable only  by  the  intellect.  This  does  not  prevent  it 
from  being  a  real  substantial  entity,  though  an  incomplete 
and  potential  one. 

The  word  used  by  Aristotle  (vA.77)  means  literally  timber, 
and  more  specifically  ship's  timbers.  Prof.  A.  E.  Taylor 
suggests  that  its  selection  may  be  due  to  a  reminiscence  of  an 
old  Pythagorean  fancy  which  looked  on  the  universe  as  a 
ship.  It  is  most  nearly  rendered  in  our  language  by  the  word 
'stuff.' 

Form.    The  difference  between  the  Platonic  and  Aris- 


THOMISTIC  THEORY   OF  MATTER  41 

totelean  conceptions  is  as  marked  with  respect  to  their 
notions  of  Form,  as  it  is  with  respect  to  those  of  matter. 

Though  both  used  the  same  word  for  form  (efSos),  Plato 
conceived  of  it  as  a  nature  which  was  self-subsistent,  and 
separate  from  matter,  though  imaged  or  '  participated  '  in  it ; 
while  Aristotle  strongly  maintained  that  forms  must  be  an 
integral  part  of  the  things  to  which  they  give  a  determinate 
nature,  immersed  in  the  matter  of  such  things,  and  incapable 
of  being  separated  from  it.  In  a  word,  the  Platonic  forms 
are  essentially  discarnate,  and  immaterial ;  while  for  Aris- 
totle they  are  incarnate  in  matter  ;  so  that  matter  is  never 
found  without  form,  and  form  is  the  correlative  of  matter. 

The  Aristotelean  description  of  form  is  therefore  :  First 
Act,  which  constitutes,  when  joined  with  first  matter,  a  being 
which  is  one  in  essence,  and  complete. 

The  word  act  signifies  that  form  is  a  positive  perfection, 
and  first  that  it  is  immediately  joined  to  matter  in  contra- 
distinction to  accidental  form  which  presupposes  an  already 
constituted  thing,  which  it  modifies. 

The  theory  that  all  bodies  are  composed  of  a  permanent 
featureless  element,  which  is  matter,  and  positive  determin- 
ing elements  or  forms,  arose  historically  speaking  from  the 
consideration  of  the  conversion  of  one  substance  into 
another,  as  in  the  case  of  a  mixture,  such  as  beer,  which 
apparently  has  a  different  nature  from  that  of  any  of  its 
ingredients,  or  in  the  case  of  conversions  of  one  substance 
into  another,  as  water  into  steam,  wood  into  ashes  under  the 
influence  of  fire,  or  in  the  case  of  organic  conversions  such  as 
that  of  water  and  other  elements  into  the  juice  of  the  grape. 
Such  changes  are  known  as  substantial  changes.  In  recent 
times  doubt  has  been  thrown  on  the  existence  of  such 
changes,  modern  chemical  and  physical  theory  seeming  to 
show  that  they  are  in  fact  merely  new  accidental  combina- 
tions of  the  original  atoms.  Some  Scholastics,  therefore,  as 
Pere  Descoqs,  S.J.,  would  abandon  the  classical  argument 
from  substantial  change,  which  has  always  been  used  to 
establish  the  theory  of  matter  and  form.  It  seems,  however, 
that  the  theory  stands  or  falls  with  the  reality  of  such 
changes,  the  alternative  to  accepting  them  being  a  denial  of 


42  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

all  essential  or  specific  difference  between  things.  It  is  to 
this  denial  that  the  current  scientific  theories  would  naturally 
lead,  and  it  is  a  denial  which  no  Scholastic  would  make  :  for, 
as  has  been  pointed  out,  the  backbone  of  the  philosophy  of 
nature,  as  conceived  by  Scholasticism  of  any  type,  is  the 
maintenance  of  the  essential  differences  between  bodies,  and 
the  rebuttal  of  monism.  Those  writers  who  wish  to  abandon 
the  argument  from  substantial  change  suggest  that  the  series 
of  chemical  elements  are  such  specifically  distinct  natures  : 
but  this  contention  is  based  on  precisely  the  same  grounds 
as  those  which  lead  the  Thomists  to  say  that  compound 
natures,  such  as  water  and  oil,  are  specifically  distinct,  viz., 
that  they  exhibit  constant  and  sharply  distinguished  proper- 
ties.1 Further,  the  whole  tendency  of  natural  science  is  to 
reduce  all  the  chemical  elements  to  a  single  base,  such  as 
hydrogen  ;  and  if  scientific  results  be  taken  as  being  applic- 
able as  they  stand  to  philosophical  discussion,  a  man  who  is 
ready  to  give  up  specific  differences  among  compounds,  on 
the  ground  that  science  does  not  recognise  them,  should  also 
be  ready  to  abandon  specific  differences  altogether,  even 
between  simple  bodies,  if  science  should  not  acknowledge 
them. 

The  Aristotelean  and  Thomistic  theory  as  to  the  constitu- 
tion of  bodies  therefore  maintains,  as  we  have  seen,  that  their 
constituents  are  two  principles,  which  are  intrinsic  and  dis- 
tinct, viz.  matter  and  form  ;  and  to  prove  it  S.  Thomas 
appeals  in  the  first  place  to  the  fact  of  substantial  change, 
for  it  is  clear  that  every  change  implies  a  subject  which 
changes,  and  a  substantial  change,  i.e.  the  change  of  one 
substance  into  another,  a  substantial  subject ;  otherwise  we 
should  have  annihilation  and  creation,  not  change.  Now, 
since  this  subject  is  to  be  common  to  two  specifically  distinct 
substances,  it  must  not  of  itself  possess  the  specific  character 
of  either,  and  will  therefore  of  itself  be  altogether  undeter- 
mined and  featureless.  Such  a  subject  or  substratum  is  what 
we  have  called  first  matter.  Similarly,  if  bodies  are  sub- 
stantially mutable,  they  must  include  a  second  principle 

1  Cf.  P.  Geny,  S.J.,  De  doctrina  Hylemorphica.  Divus  Thomas  (Plac), 
January  1925. 


THOMISTIC  THEORY   OF   MATTER  43 

which  completes  and  specifies  this  quite  undifferentiated  and 
potential  subject,  otherwise  they  would  have  no  definite 
character,  and  so  could  not  change  from  one  character  to 
another.  It  is  further  clear  that  these  two  principles  are 
really  distinct,  from  the  fact  that  they  are  separable  and 
separated  in  the  process  of  change,  since  the  potential 
subject  remains  the  same,  while  the  form  is  altered,  the  prior 
form  disappearing  from  the  subject, which  thereupon  receives 
a  new  form.  Hence  the  subject  and  the  form  are  separated 
and  distinct. 

The  a  posteriori  foundation  of  the  theory  remains,  how- 
ever, still  to  be  proved,  viz.  that  substantial  changes  actually 
occur  :  or  that  bodies  are  substantially  mutable.  It  is 
necessary  to  prove  this  for  all  bodies,  both  organic  and 
inorganic,  though  not  that  such  changes  actually  occur  in 
every  body,  since  our  purpose  is  to  show  that  it  is  the  nature 
of  body  to  be  capable  of  such  change,  even  if,  as  may  happen, 
they  have  not  been  subject  to  it,  or  the  change  has  not  been 
observed  in  them.  Now,  if  we  prove  our  general  rule  for 
organic  bodies,  this  will  afford  an  a  priori  presumption  that 
it  holds  good  for  inorganic  bodies  also,  otherwise,  the  organic, 
as  mutable,  would  be  inferior  to  the  inorganic  which  would 
be  immutable.  For  the  immutable  is  more  perfect  than  the 
mutable,  since  that  which  is  absolutely  perfect  must  be 
wholly  unchangeable,  and  change  lessens  as  perfection  grows. 

1.  Taking,  then,  the  case  of  organic  bodies  we  have  the 
very  simple  and  evident  fact  that  plants  and  animals  die, 
and  the  no  less  clear  fact  that  the  animal  and  its  dead  body 
are  specifically  distinct,  since  their  operations  differ  essen- 
tially, those  of  the  one  being  immanent,  springing  from  an 
intrinsic  principle  and  being  directed  towards  the  good  of 
the  whole  animal,  whereas  those  of  the  other  are  transeunt 
only,  the  term  of  decomposition  being  the  disintegration  and 
destruction  of  the  body.  Clearly,  however,  they  could  not 
act  in  these  essentially  different  ways  unless  they  were  essen- 
tially different  in  themselves.  Similarly,  organic  things 
transmute  inorganic  ones  into  their  own  substance  in  the 
process  of  nutrition.  Hence,  it  follows  that  in  the  organic 
realm  as  a  whole,  substantial  change  occurs  ;    since  the 


44  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

organic  bodies  either  change  themselves,  or  produce  substan- 
tial changes  in  the  inorganic  bodies  which  they  absorb. 

2.  Passing  now  to  the  realm  of  inorganic  matter,  we  observe 
the  continued  formation  of  elements  into  new  compounds,  the 
elements  and  compounds  being  specifically  distinct.  That 
the  latter  part  of  this  statement  is  true  is  shown  from  finality, 
for  things  which  have  different  finalistic  inclinations  or  ten- 
dencies must  be  specifically  distinct,  since  such  tendency  is 
nothing  else  than  nature  itself  which  is  tending  to  a  definite 
end  :  hence,  where  it  is  different,  it  follows  we  have  two 
different  natural  tendencies,  which  must  therefore  be  imman- 
ent in  the  things  themselves  (since  nature  is  immanent),  and 
constitute  them  as  naturally  or  specifically  distinct. 

That  such  different  finalistic  tendencies  do  exist  in  the 
elements  and  their  compound  is  an  obvious  fact  of  experi- 
ence ;  for  all  simple  bodies  act  in  a  certain  definite  way,  and 
combine  according  to  certain  ascertained  laws ;  and,  similarly, 
composite  bodies  have  their  own  distinctive  actions  and  laws 
which  differ  from  those  of  the  simple  ones.  To  take  the 
obvious  case  of  water  and  its  elements  to  illustrate  this,  we 
know  that  oxygen  and  hydrogen  produce  their  own  distinc- 
tive effects,  and  combine  only  in  certain  proportions.  Water, 
however,  which  is  their  compound,  has  its  own  action  which 
is  quite  different  from  either  of  theirs,  and  in  some  ways  in 
opposition  to  their  actions,  and  it  also  obeys  its  own  proper 
laws.  Thus  all  bodies  have  their  own  distinctive  finalistic 
tendencies. 

3.  Another  argument  to  show  the  fact  of  substantial 
change  is  derived  from  the  unity  of  bodies. 

It  is  indubitably  true  that  a  thing  which  possesses  one, 
and  only  one,  nature  cannot  be  made  of  a  number  of  things 
possessing  different  natures.  Now,  if  we  consider  nutrition 
in  plants  and  animals,  we  see  that  they  absorb  into  them- 
selves many  things  which  before  absorption  have  a  complete 
and  independent  nature  of  their  own,  a  nature  which  is  lost 
when  they  are  taken  up  into  the  body  of  the  animal  or  plant 
which  feeds  on  them  :  for  if  not,  it  would  follow  that  the 
living  thing  was  but  the  sum  total  of  the  things  on  which  it 
feeds,  and  not  a  complete  essential  unity  on  its  own  account. 


THOMISTIC  THEORY  OF  MATTER  45 

If,  then,  it  is  such  an  essential  unity,  it  is  clear  that  the  sub- 
stances on  which  it  feeds  undergo  a  substantial  change. 
Hardly  anyone  would  doubt  the  essential  unity  of  living 
things,  since  all  their  functions  and  activities  are  directed 
towards  the  good  of  the  plant  or  animal  as  a  whole,  not  to 
that  of  some  particular  part  of  it.  In  nutrition,  for  example, 
the  whole  being  feeds  and  is  nourished,  not  the  mouth, 
stomach  or  any  particular  organ  in  isolation.  In  man,  whom 
we  know  more  intimately  than  we  do  any  other  animal,  this 
is  particularly  clear,  for  we  say  the  man,  e.g.  John,  thinks, 
feels  and  eats  :  not  that  John's  brain  thinks,  John's  hands 
feel,  and  John's  stomach  eats.  If  John  were  not  a  unity,  but 
a  mere  collection  of  elements  and  organs,  such  an  attribution 
of  all  these  functions  to  him  would  be  altogether  illegitimate. 
We  are  conscious,  however,  that  it  is  not  so,  and  the  whole 
human  race  agrees  with  us.1 

Besides  this  classical  argument  from  the  fact  of  substantial 
change,  there  are  two  other  metaphysical  arguments  which 
are  ordinarily  used  by  Scholastics  to  prove  that  bodies 
are  composed  of  matter  and  form,  i.e.  of  an  undetermined 
principle  which  is  capable  of  becoming  anything  :  which 
S.  Thomas  calls  a  potency  or  potentiality  ;  and  a  perfecting 
and  determining  one,  which  he  calls  act. 

These  arguments  for  their  full  understanding  need  more 
precise  acquaintance  with  metaphysical  notions  than  is 
possible  at  this  stage  ;  it  is  nevertheless  worth  while  to  note 
them  here  owing  to  their  demonstrative  character. 

1.  The  first  of  these  arguments  is  based  on  the  fact  of 
extension,  for  it  is  clear,  that  since  all  bodies  are  extended, 
they  can  be  divided  into  parts  of  the  same  nature  as  the 
original  body,  as  slices  of  bread  are  still  bread.  It  is  clear, 
then,  that  all  bodies  have  a  certain  capacity  for  division,  or 
what  is  the  same  thing,  for  multiplication.  (Cf.  II  Contra 
Gentiles,  c.  65,  Arg.  3.)  Such  a  capacity  is,  however,  what  we 
call  a  potentiality  or  potency,  and  it  follows  that  all  bodies 
possess  an  element  which  is  potential.  They  are  nevertheless 
not  entirely  composed  of  this  element,  for  they  are  always 

1  This  is  more  fully  discussed  in  the  Psychological  section  later.  Vied 
Ch.  IV  and  Ch.  XV. 


46  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

definite  bodies  of  some  kind,  i.e.  they  possess  an  actual 
element  also  ;  in  other  words,  all  bodies  are  composed  of 
potency  and  act,  i.e.  of  matter  and  form. 

2.  Again,  if  we  consider  a  whole  species  instead  of  an 
individual  body,  we  shall  be  led  to  the  same  conclusion  :  for 
it  is  clear  that  in  order  that  one  and  the  same  specific  nature 
may  be  found  in  several  individuals,  it  must  be  differentiated 
in  them  in  some  way,  i.e.  there  must  be  something  which  is 
added  to  the  specific  nature  in  each  of  them.  If  each  were 
simply  the  specific  nature,  and  nothing  more,  they  would  not 
be  different  individuals.  Now,  the  nature  itself  is  a  definite 
determined  thing,  i.e.  a  perfection  or  an  act ;  and  therefore 
the  individual  must  possess  an  element  which  is  different 
from  this  act,  and  at  the  same  time  is  capable  of  receiving  it. 
Such  a  capacity,  however,  is  what  we  mean  by  potency,  and 
so  the  individual  is  composed  of  two  elements,  an  actual  one 
and  a  potential  one,  i.e.  form  and  matter. 

The  reason  why,  in  both  these  arguments,  we  identify 
the  actual  and  potential  elements  in  the  individual  with 
substantial  form  and  first  matter,  is  that  the  individual  must 
be  a  unity  and  an  essential  unity,  for  it  is  certainly  one  thing, 
not  two.  Now  the  greatest  amount  of  division  that  is  possible 
in  a  unity  of  this  kind  is  the  division  into  a  potency  and  its 
immediate  act,  for  if  the  potency  were  made  actually  a  sub- 
stance, any  further  act  would  only  modify  the  already  exist- 
ing substance,  i.e.  it  would  be  an  accident ;  and  the  union 
would  be  accidental.  Undetermined  and  unactuated  potency, 
such  as  this,  is  precisely  what  we  mean  by  first  matter,  as  the 
definition  given  above  shows,  while  its  immediate  act  is  sub- 
stantial form.  Consequently,  in  order  to  preserve  the  essen- 
tial unity  of  the  individual  it  is  necessary  for  us  to  say  that 
its  potential  element  is  first  matter,  and  its  actual  element 
substantial  form. 

A  Further  Consideration  of  Matter  and  Form. 

We  now  pass  to  a  consideration  of  the  two  principles  of 
bodies,  taken  individually. 

What  exactly  are  first  matter  and  substantial  form  ?  In 
the  first  place  we  ask  with  regard  to  first  matter  :   is  it  pure 


THOMISTIC  THEORY   OF  MATTER  47 

potentiality  ?  By  pure  potentiality  is  meant  that  which  does 
not  contain  any  act  as  a  part  of  itself,  and  that  which  has  not 
the  nature  of  act  in  any  real  order.  Now,  there  are  two  real 
orders,  those,  namely,  of  essence  and  existence,  and  so  a  two- 
fold act  :  act  of  essence  and  act  of  existence,  or,  as  they  are 
often  called,  formal  and  entitative  act.  The  first  determines 
what  the  thing  is,  the  second  places  the  thing  outside  the 
state  of  mere  possibility,  making  it  an  actually  existing 
thing.  So,  in  the  case  of  a  child,  every  child  whether  possible 
or  existing  is  a  certain  kind  of  animal,  an  animal  which  is 
capable  of  loving,  thinking,  laughing  and  talking  ;  of  a  par- 
ticular physical  shape  and  organisation,  and  so  on  ;  but 
before  such  a  child  is  conceived  it  is  possible  only,  it  may  be 
born  ;  but  when  it  is  born  or  conceived,  it  has  not  only  the 
formal  act  which  belonged  to  it  when  it  was  still  only 
possible,  but  in  addition  the  act  or  perfection  of  existing,  by 
whose  means  it  makes  its  appearance  in  the  world,  as  an 
actually  existing  member  of  a  family. 

That  matter  is  pure  potentiality  in  the  order  of  essence  is 
universally  admitted  by  Scholastics,  i.e.  all  agree  that  it  has 
no  determined  nature  of  its  own,  being  a  mere  capacity  for 
receiving  form,  or  in  technical  language,  that  it  is  free  of  all 
formal  act,  and  so  has  no  element  of  form  in  it,  nor  is  it  to 
be  thought  of  as  form,  either  in  itself,  or  relatively  to  any 
real  subject  which  is  naturally  prior  to  it.  So,  no  material 
element,  however  all-pervasive,  or  capable  of  being  a  sub- 
stratum in  various  substances,  as  oxygen  for  example,  nor 
even  any  definite  force,  such  as  electricity,  can  possibly  be 
identified  with  first  matter  ;  since  all  have  their  own  original 
nature  or  form.1  It  has  therefore  an  unlimited  capacity  for 
receiving  all  material  forms  ;  though  not,  of  course,  for 
receiving  those  which  are  wholly  immaterial,  if  there  are  any 
such,  since  these  would  not  be  in  any  way  correlative  to  it. 
Just  as  a  quart  measure  can  receive  any  quantity  up  to  a 

1  How  easy  it  is  to  be  entirely  mistaken  as  to  the  meaning  of  first 
matter  is  exemplified  in  the  following  astonishing  statement  (Haas,  The 
New  Physics,  p.  71)  :  '  In  the  modern  system  of  physics  electricity  no 
longer  stands  alongside  of  matter  :  it  has  taken  the  place  of  matter.  The 
new  physics  can  descry  in  electricity  that  unadulterated  primordial 
something  for  which  scientists  sought  through  thousands  of  years,  and 
from  which  all  things  amenable  to  sense  perception  are  formed.' 


48  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

quart,  so  that,  to  this  extent,  its  capacity  is  unlimited  ;  so 
first  matter  is  like  a  vessel  which  should  be  capable  of  receiv- 
ing any  amount  however  great ;  which  would  nevertheless 
not  be  capable  of  receiving  anything  which  was  not  quantita- 
tive. It  has  an  indefinite  internal  capacity,  though  externally 
it  is  limited. 

Here,  however,  agreement  ends  ;  for  many  hold  that  there 
is  in  matter  some  entitative  act,  while  others  will  not  allow 
it  to  have  any  of  itself.  This  question  is  closely  connected 
with  the  more  famous  one  with  regard  to  the  real  distinction 
between  essence  and  existence.  Those  who  deny  the  real 
distinction  must  hold  that  the  essence  of  matter  is  its  exis- 
tence, and  since  existence  is  necessarily  actual,  that  this 
essence  is  an  entitative  act,  though  an  incomplete  one.  For 
they  say  that  it  is  impossible  to  conceive  of  anything  being 
real,  unless  it  has  existence  which  is  identified  with  itself. 
This  is  the  opinion  of  the  Scotists,  Suarez  and  others.  For 
those  who  hold,  with  S.  Thomas,  the  real  distinction,  the 
question  can  only  be,  whether  matter  has  some  existence  of 
its  own,  independently  of  form  ;  in  other  words,  whether 
matter  is  related  to  existence  immediately,  without  form 
intervening,  or  whether  it  receives  existence  only  by  the 
mediation  of  form.  This  latter  view,  which  is  universal 
among  Thomists,  is  an  integral  part  of  the  Aristotelean  notion 
of  form,  since,  for  him,  existence  belongs  to  form  of  itself  (per 
se),  to  matter  by  means  of  something  else,  viz.  form  (per 
aliud).  The  Thomists  therefore  have  to  prove  that  matter 
has  no  existence  of  its  own.  To  do  so  they  argue  once  more 
from  the  essential  unity  of  the  individual,  for  if  matter  has 
its  own  existence,  form  can  only  give  it  an  added  or  secondary 
existence,  which  therefore  cannot  make  it  simply  existing, 
but  merely  existing  in  a  certain  new  way.  In  other  words, 
it  will  not  make  it  exist  as  a  substance,  but  confer  an  added 
accidental  existence,  so  that  matter  and  form  together  will 
not  be  substance,  but  substance  and  accident. 

Further,  an  essential  unity  cannot  have  two  substantial 
existences,  which  would  be  the  case  if  matter  has  its  own 
existence,  as  well  as  form.  So,  from  both  points  of  view,  it  is 
clear  that  if  matter  has  its  own  existence,  the  compound 


THOMISTIC  THEORY   OF  MATTER  49 

resulting  from  matter  and  form  will  not  be  an  essential,  but 
only  an  accidental  unity. 

This  same  truth  can  also  be  proved  as  follows  :  It  is  clear 
that  if  matter  can  only  receive  existence  by  the  mediation 
of  form,  it  has  no  existence  of  its  own  ;  and  that  this  is,  in 
fact,  the  case,  we  see  if  we  consider  that  existence  can  only 
belong,  of  itself,  either  to  a  complete  essence,  or,  at  most,  to 
some  actual  principle  of  essence  ;  since  a  thing  which  exists 
must  be  a  determinate  and  definite  thing,  otherwise,  we 
should  be  in  the  absurd  position  of  asserting  that  something 
altogether  indefinite  exists.  It  is,  however,  clear  that  matter 
is  neither  a  complete  nature,  nor  yet  an  actual  principle  of 
nature,  since  it  is  defined  as  a  capacity  for  receiving  form, 
i.e.  as  a  potential  principle  of  nature.  It  follows,  therefore, 
that  we  cannot  consistently  maintain  that  matter  has  any 
existence  of  its  own. 

That  matter  has  no  formal  act,  on  which  all  Scholastics 
agree,  is  simply  another  way  of  stating  the  definition  of  it  : 
'  neque  quid,  neque  quale,  etc'  ;  and  it  is  clear  that  unless  this 
fundamental  notion  of  matter  is  adhered  to,  it  is  useless  to 
employ  the  notion  at  all,  since  matter  which  includes  formal 
act  will  be  a  mixture  of  matter  and  form,  so  that  either  we 
must  go  on  for  ever  with  a  series  of  matters  which  include 
form,  or  else  say  that  at  last  we  come  to  a  matter  free  from 
formal  act,  which  is  what  Aristotle  and  the  Scholastics 
understand  by  the  expression  '  first  matter.' 

If,  then,  it  be  granted  that  first  matter  is  pure  potency, 
certain  other  conclusions  with  regard  to  it  immediately  follow : 

1.  It  is  metaphysically  impossible  for  matter  to  exist 
without  form,  since  it  receives  its  existence  by  the  mediation 
of  form. 

2.  From  which  it  follows  that  matter  is  unknowable  apart 
from  form,  since  that  which  cannot  be,  or  exist,  cannot  be 
known.  So  all  our  knowledge  of  first  matter  is  derived  from 
some  compound  of  matter  and  form,  and  Butler  rightly 
derides  the  pseudo-philosopher  who  asserts  that  : 

'  He  had  first  matter  seen  undressed  ; 
He  took  her  naked  all  alone, 
Before  one  rag  of  form  was  on.'1 
1  Hudibras,  Part  I,  Canto  I. 


50  MODERN  THOMOSTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

So  matter  being  a  correlative  of  form  is  only  intelligible 
with  relation  to  it,  we  must  know  of  what  it  is  capable  if  we 
are  to  understand  its  capacity ;  just  as  a  Fiji  Islander,  if 
confronted  with  an  electric  accumulator,  and  asked  what  its 
capacity  was,  would  reply,  in  all  probability,  that  it  could 
hold  about  two  pints,  not  knowing  that  it  had  a  capacity  for 
storing  electrical  energy,  and  that  this  was  what  it  was  made 
for.  He  could  only  understand  the  accumulator  if  he  under- 
stood that  of  which  it  was  capable. 

3.  We  must  further  conclude  that  if  matter  receives 
existence  from  substantial  form  only,  there  can  be  only  one 
substantial  form  in  one  compound.  This  is  a  much-debated 
question,  about  which  more  will  be  said  later.1  Here  it  is 
sufficient  to  note  that  there  are  three  main  opinions  with 
regard  to  it.  The  first  is  that  of  Scotus,  who  contends  that  a 
living  body  possesses,  besides  the  soul  which  is  united  to  it, 
an  incomplete  and  subordinate  form,  called  corporeality 
(corporeitas).  The  second  view  is  that  of  Albert  the  Great, 
who  was  S.  Thomas'  master,  and  some  modern  writers, 
according  to  whom  the  soul  would  be  the  primary  form  of  the 
body,  and  the  forms  of  the  chemical  elements  would  be  sub- 
sumed by  it,  retaining  their  natural  reality.  The  third 
opinion  is  that  there  is  only  one  substantial  form  in  one  com- 
pound, and  is  that  of  S.  Thomas  and  all  Thomists.2 

As  M.  Nys  says,  the  reasons  given  by  S.  Thomas  appear 
to  be  decisive. 

He  argues  :  one  thing  has  only  one  substantial  being,  but 
substantial  being  is  given  by  substantial  form  (as  we  have 
just  seen),  therefore  one  thing  has  only  one  substantial  form. 
Secondly,  there  is  no  mean  between  substantial  and  accidental 
form,  hence,  if  there  is  a  first  form  which  gives  substantial 
being,  any  other  which  is  added  to  it  will  find  the  subject 
already  constituted  as  a  substantial  being,  and  consequently 
will  be  accidentally  united  to  it.3 

4.  Since,  then,  matter  is  pure  potency,  and  form,  act 
which  confers  existence  on  matter,  and  makes  the  material 

1  Vide  pp.  129  ff.,  Ch.  X,  Qu.  1. 

2  Cf.  Remer,  Cosmologia,  pp.  87  ff.  (ed.  4a,  192 1). 

3  Summa  Theol.,  Part  I,  Q.  76,  Arts.  3,  4  ;  de.  Potentia,  Q.  3,  Ch.  3,  et  9 
ad  9. 


THOMISTIC  THEORY  OF  MATTER  51 

thing  a  being,  it  follows  that  form  of  itself  actuates  matter, 
and  makes  the  compound  of  matter  and  form  a  unity.  In 
other  words,  there  is  no  need,  in  order  that  matter  and  form 
should  be  made  one,  of  any  unifying  medium  distinct  from 
them,  just  as  in  cabinet-making  when  parts  are  dovetailed, 
there  is  no  need  of  glue  to  join  them. 

From  all  that  has  been  said  of  substantial  form,  it  will  be 
obvious  that  it  is  not  the  same  as  what  is  commonly  called 
form,  in  everyday  language,  as  when  we  speak  about  the 
form  of  a  vase.  This  really  means  its  shape,  though  there  is 
no  doubt  a  vague  reminiscence  of  the  old  meaning  of  form, 
as  that  which  gives  a  thing  its  definite  character. 

The  question  is  often  asked  whether  this  theory  of  matter 
and  form  is  compatible  with  the  results  of  modern  science, 
since  spectroscopic  investigation  has  proved,  from  a  scientific 
point  of  view,  that  the  chemical  elements  remain  in  the 
molecule,  or  larger  body,  intact,  and  so  are  not  substantially 
changed,  and,  even  in  living  things,  scientific  investigation 
seems  to  show  that  elements  absorbed  in  the  process  of 
nutrition  are  not  changed  in  their  natures,  but  merely  used 
by  the  living  thing  to  build  up  its  tissues,  etc.  ;  which  results 
would  destroy  our  first  argument.  What  is,  perhaps,  even 
more  serious,  though  all  of  a  piece  with  the  denial  of  sub- 
stantial change,  is  that  science  does  not  recognise  the  con- 
tinuity of  matter,  nor  the  unity  of  bodies  ;  since,  in  the 
scientific  view,  the  atom  itself  is  made  up  of  discontinuous 
electrons  and  nuclei,  the  abandonment  of  the  old  notion  of 
the  ether  making  this  discontinuity  still  more  apparent.  If, 
however,  there  is  neither  continuity  nor  unity  in  matter  our 
other  two  arguments  fall  to  the  ground. 

To  answer  these  difficulties  completely,  a  treatise  on  the 
nature  and  scope  of  scientific  theories  would  be  required  ; 
but  it  will  be  sufficient  for  our  present  purpose  to  note  the 
following  considerations  : 

1.  The  scientist  does  not  approach  the  investigation  of  the 
physical  world  with  the  same  aim  as  the  philosopher,  for  he 
wishes  to  observe  the  phenomena  accurately,  not  to  discover 
the  ultimate  nature  of  the  bodies  whose  appearances  they 
are.    Thus  his  theories  or  pictures  of  bodies,  if  he  presents 


52  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

any,  are  all  directed  to  the  elucidation  of  the  phenomena 
themselves,  not  of  what  lies  behind  them,  if  anything  does  : 
whereas  it  is  the  nature  of  the  underlying  reality  which  is 
precisely  that  which  interests  the  philosopher. 

2.  Exact  science  can  only  speak  in  terms  of  quantity, 
neglecting  all  else,  such  as  nature  and  quality  ;  whereas  the 
philosopher  has  to  take  every  aspect  of  the  physical  universe 
into  account. 

3.  From  the  account  given  above  of  the  Thomistic  theory 
of  matter,  it  will  be  clear  that  it  is  essentially  a  metaphysical 
theory,  which  enunciates  the  elements  which  bodies  must 
possess  if  we  are  to  give  an  intelligible  account  of  matter  and 
motion  ;  taking  all  bodies,  including  our  own,  into  consider- 
ation. Such  a  view  is  evidently  much  wider  and  deeper  than 
the  special  one  of  physics,  and  it  follows  that  the  scientific 
theories  and  conclusions  cannot  be  transported  bodily,  and  as 
they  stand,  into  the  philosophical  theory.  Further,  the  fact 
that  science  with  its  special  aim,  and  using  its  own  proper 
methods,  does  not  find  essential  change  or  continuity  in  the 
material  world,  does  not  prove  that  these  do  not  exist  there, 
and  if  reason  demands  that  we  should  assert  their  existence, 
our  conviction  of  the  truth  of  this  assertion  is  not  weakened 
by  the  fact  that  the  description  which  science  gives  of 
matter,  for  its  own  purposes,  does  not  confirm  it :  nor  would 
it  be  strengthened  if  science  did  so  confirm  it.  So  Fr.  D'Arcy 
says  :  '  Whatever  scientific  hypothesis  of  nature  be  accepted, 
evolutionary  or  static,  the  principles  of  S.  Thomas  find  a 
ready  application.  They  serve  to  explain  the  presuppositions 
of  fixity  and  change,  and  disclose  the  two  factors  which  must 
be  assumed  and  included  in  any  intelligible  account.  The 
physical  theory  of  S.  Thomas  need  be  taken  ...  as  only  a 
framework  into  which  a  variety  of  scientific  theories  can  be 
fitted.    It  is  primarily  metaphysical.'1 

4.  If  we  examine,  in  the  light  of  these  principles,  the 
particular  instances  in  which  we  have  asserted  the  reality  of 
substantial  change  and  continuity,  we  shall  see  that  the 

1  M.  C.  D'Arcy,  S.J.,  Thomas  Aequinas,  pp.  196  flf.  Benn,  Leaders  of 
Philosophy  Series  (1930).  Cf.  P.  Geny,  S.J.,  Art.  in  Divus  Thomas  (Plac), 
January  1925,  pp.  73  flf. 


THOMISTIC  THEORY  OF  MATTER  53 

conclusions  of  science,  in  so  far  as  they  seem  to  point  to  a 
denial  of  their  reality,  are,  in  fact,  based  on  a  consideration 
of  the  facts,  which  is  only  partial.  So,  substantial  change 
would  be  denied  chiefly  on  the  ground  that  spectroscopic 
analysis  shows  that  the  elements  of  the  molecule  remain  in 
it ;  and  continuity,  because  different  properties  are  found 
in  different  parts  of  the  molecule  or  atom.  No  consideration 
is  taken,  however,  of  the  further  fact  that  the  molecule 
operates  as  a  whole,  and  as  a  whole  has  properties  which  are 
quite  distinct  from  those  of  its  elements,  nor  of  the  fact  that 
whatever  might  be  said  of  the  discontinuity  of  inorganic 
matter,  it  is  impossible  to  deny  that  living  bodies,  at  least, 
are  unities.  If  we  take  these  considerations  into  account  we 
shall  conclude,  not  to  simple  heterogeneity,  which  would 
exclude  substantial  change  and  continuity,  but  to  a  sub- 
stantial unity  accompanied  by  accidental  heterogeneity  ; 
for  it  is  not  a  sufficient  criterion  for  the  real  discontinuity  of 
bodies  to  point  out  that  the  parts  of  them  have  differing 
properties,  we  must  also  show  that  there  is  no  solid  ground 
for  supposing  them  to  be  continuous.  Thus,  a  horse  and  his 
rider  exhibit  different  properties,  and  there  is  no  reason 
why  we  should  suppose  them  to  be  parts  of  one  substance, 
so  we  conclude  they  are  different  and  discontinuous,  whereas 
a  man's  blood  and  the  rest  of  his  body,  though  exhibiting 
different  properties,  are  nevertheless  not  judged  to  be 
different  substances,  or  discontinuous,  since  the  man  is 
evidently  a  unity  :  all  the  constituents  of  his  body,  including 
his  blood,  working  in  harmony  for  the  sake  of  the  whole. 

We  conclude,  therefore,  that  the  theory  of  S.  Thomas,  with 
regard  to  the  nature  of  bodies,  remains  unaffected  in  its 
essentials  by  modern  scientific  investigations  ;  and  that,  in 
fact,  all  bodies  are  composed  of  matter  and  form. 


CHAPTER   IV 

QUANTITY 

The  Distinction  of  Quantity  and  Substance — Descartes'  View — 
Reasons  for  Affirming  the  Distinction — The  Nature  of  the 
Distinction — The  Nature  of  Quantity  in  Itself — Its  Effects — 
Opinions — The  Usual  Thomist  View — Reasons  in  its  Favour — 
A  Difficulty  Considered — The  Separability  of  Quantity  and 
Substance  :  Substance  without  Quantity,  Quantity  without 
Substance — A  Peculiarity  of  Quantity. 

After  the  discussion  on  the  nature  of  material  things, 
logical  order  leads  us  to  consider  their  primary  character- 
istics, which  are  quantity  and  quality :  for,  as  S.  Thomas 
says,  "  The  first  accidents  which  follow  substance  are 
quantity  and  quality,  and  these  two  are  proportionate  to 
the  two  essential  principles  of  substance,  viz.  form  and 
matter."1 

Quantity  is  usually  denned  by  the  Scholastics  as  :  '  an 
accident,  which  makes  the  subject  have  parts  outside  parts.' 
They  further  distinguish  two  kinds  of  quantity,  continuous 
quantity,  or  extension,  and  discrete  quantity  or  number. 
Now,  it  is  evident  that  things  are  actually  numerable  in  so 
far  as  they  are  separate,  and  they  are  separated  by  division. 
So  that  discrete  quantity  is  a  derivative  of  continuous, 
brought  about  by  the  separation  of  one  part  of  it  from 
another  ;  by  cutting  it  up,  in  fact,  in  the  way  in  which  from 
one  loaf  of  certain  dimensions  (continuous  quantity)  we  get 
a  number  of  slices  of  bread  (discrete  quantity).  However, 
as  is  clear  from  this,  continuous  quantity  is  the  primary 
kind  of  quantity,  and  so  we  shall,  here,  be  principally 
interested  in  it. 

Two  questions  immediately  suggest  themselves  when  we 
look  at  the  definition  given  above  :    first,  is  it  true  that 

1  IV  Sent.  dist.  XII,  Q.  i,  a.  i. 
54 


QUANTITY  55 

quantity  is  an  accident,  or  is  it  to  be  identified  with  the 
substance  of  body  ?  Secondly,  what  precisely  do  we  mean 
by  saying  that  it  makes  the  subject  have  parts  outside 
parts,  i.e.  what  is  the  precise  nature  of  quantity  ?  This 
question  is  expressed  in  Scholastic  language  by  asking  : 
what  is  its  primary  formal  effect  ? 

Question  I.     7s  Quantity  Distinct  from  Substance  ? 

Some  philosophers,  as  was  to  be  expected,  hold  that 
quantity  is  really  distinct  from  substance,  and  some  that  it 
is  not.  Among  those  who  admit,  at  least  to  some  extent,  the 
truth  of  the  Aristotelean  notion  of  two  distinct  realities  in 
bodies,  substance  and  accident,  there  are  still  some  who 
make  an  exception  in  the  case  of  quantity.  Thus  Descartes, 
while  acknowledging  a  modal  distinction  between  accident 
and  substance,  i.e.  that  some  accidents  affect  substance 
variably,  nevertheless  asserted  that  the  nature  of  physical 
body  is  extension  in  three  dimensions,  and  so  identified  its 
substance  with  extension.1  The  distinction  of  substance 
from  quantity  is  also  evidently  denied  by  those  who  do  not 
recognise  the  distinction  between  substance  and  accidents  in 
general,  as  Hume  and  the  Phenomenalist  School,  together 
with  the  Monists,  and  the  majority  of  modern  philosophers. 
The  dispute,  however,  is,  in  this  case,  clearly  not  confined  to 
the  question  of  quantity. 

That  substance  and  quantity  are  really  distinct  is  the 
opinion  of  all  Scholastics,  with  the  possible  exception  of  the 
Nominalists ;  though  they  differ  in  the  way  in  which  they 
understand  this  distinction. 

Various  arguments  are  used  to  prove  the  reality  of  the 
distinction,  among  which  are  the  following  : 

i.  In  order  that  quantity  may  be  the  same  as  substance, 
it  is  necessary  that  it  should  be  the  same,  either  as  the  sum 
of  the  essential  parts  of  corporeal  substance,  or,  at  least,  as 
one  of  these  parts  taken  separately.  This  is  not  the  case, 
however,  for  the  essential  constitutive  parts  of  corporeal 

1  Principes  de  la  philosophic  Partie  I,  Ch.  LX-LXII.  CEuvres,  Tom.  IX, 
ed.  Adam-Tannery.  Everyman  ed.,  Vol.  570,  p.  188.  Cf.  Principes, 
Partie  I,  CEuvres,  II,  ed.  Napoleon  Chaix,  p.  55,  in  Everyman  ed,,  Sect.  53, 
p.  185. 


56  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

substance  are  matter  and  form.  Now,  it  is  clear  that  quan- 
tity is  not  to  be  identified  with  matter,  since  matter  is  pure 
potentiality,  while  quantity  is  evidently  actual ;  for  it  either 
confers  something  actual  on  a  subject  (if  it  be  distinct  from 
its  subject),  or  is  itself  actually  extended.  Nor  can  quantity 
be  identified  with  substantial  form  ;  for  the  characteristic 
of  such  form  is  that  it  informs  the  whole  of  its  matter  in  pre- 
cisely the  same  way,  since  its  function  is  to  make  the  body 
to  be  of  a  particular  kind,  and  so,  all  of  the  same  kind,  other- 
wise we  should  have  two  species  of  bodies,  i.e.  two  forms. 
Although  form  may  be  divided,  yet,  since  it  makes  the  thing 
what  it  is,  the  whole  of  any  simple  body  has  one  and  the  same 
form  throughout,  whereas  it  evidently  does  not  have  the 
same  quantity  throughout.  A  part  is  not  equal  to  the  whole 
in  quantity,  but  it  is  the  same  in  form.  Lastly,  quantity 
cannot  be  identified  with  matter  and  form  taken  in  conjunc- 
tion, since  together  they  do  not  compose  some  third  thing, 
other  than  matter  and  form  ;  for,  as  we  have  seen,  the  union 
of  matter  and  form  is  immediate  (cf.  p.  50,  No.  4)  ;  and 
quantity  cannot  be  made  up  of  two  elements,  one  of  which  is 
potential  and  identical  with  matter,  while  the  other  is  actual 
and  identical  with  form  ;  since,  as  we  saw  above,  quantity  is 
necessarily  and  wholly  actual.  Hence,  in  no  way  can  quan- 
tity be  identified  with  corporeal  substance. 

2.  Another  simple  but  convincing  argument  is  the 
following  : 

If  quantity  were  the  same  as  corporeal  substance,  i.e. 
were  of  the  very  essence  of  corporeal  substance,  quantity 
could  not  be  varied  without  the  nature  of  the  body  being 
varied.  In  other  words,  a  change  in  quantity  would  entail  a 
specific  change  in  the  body  ;  since  the  change  of  an  essential 
element  must  necessarily  change  the  nature  of  the  body.  It 
is  clear,  however,  that  quantity  can  alter,  both  in  different 
individuals  of  the  same  species,  and  even  in  the  same 
individual  body,  by  means  of  addition  and  division,  as  well 
as  by  condensation  and  rarefaction,  without  any  such 
change  in  the  nature  of  the  body  following,  as  a  necessary 
consequence.  So  a  drop  of  water  is  water,  just  as  much  as  a 
bucketful,  or  a  lake,  from  which  it  comes,  though  evidently 


QUANTITY  57 

the  quantity  of  water  in  one  drop  is  not  the  same  as  that  in 
the  lake  ;  or  again,  a  man  remains  a  man  even  though  he 
may  grow  stout  or  lean.  His  quantity  changes,  but  his 
nature  remains  the  same. 

Granted,  then,  that  quantity  and  substance  are  not  the 
same,  we  have  now  to  consider  the  way  in  which  this  dis- 
tinction is  to  be  understood  ;  for  some  who  allow  it,  yet 
regard  as  properties  of  substance  itself,  characteristics 
which,  others  maintain,  only  accrue  to  it  from  the  influence 
of  quantity  upon  it.    Thus  : 

i.  Some  think  that  both  quantity  and  substance  have 
some  extension  of  themselves,  and  so  have  this  element  in 
common,  though  in  different  ways.  Thus  they  say  that  sub- 
stance has  entitative  extension,  i.e.  that  corporeal  substance 
has,  in  itself,  integrating  parts  ;  parts,  that  is,  which  taken 
together  make  up  the  whole  ;  so  that  it  has  such  parts  before 
the  coming  of  quantity  to  it,  the  function  of  quantity  being 
merely  to  make  these  parts  capable  of  filling  a  place,  so 
giving  impenetrability  to  the  body.  This  is  the  view  of 
Suarez.1 

2.  Others,  while  agreeing  that  substance  has  entitative 
extension  before  the  coming  of  quantity,  maintain  that  the 
special  function  of  quantity  is  to  put  the  parts  in  order.  So 
John  of  S.  Thomas.2 

3.  The  Thomists,  generally,  hold  that  though  substance 
has  no  parts  of  itself,  yet  it  obtains  parts  on  the  coming  of 
quantity  to  it. 

(Note  :  The  ascription  by  some  text-books  of  the  view 
that  substance  does  not  obtain  parts  even  under  quantity  to 
the  Salmanticenses  and  others,  seems  to  be  a  mistake. 
Cf.  Salm.,  Vol.  XVIII,  pp.  380  ff.) 

The  truth  of  the  second  part  of  this  statement,  inasmuch 
as  it  affirms  that  quantified  substance  has  parts,  is  evident, 
since  quantified  substance  is  extended  substance,  which, 
clearly,  has  parts.  To  prove  the  other  part  of  their  statement, 
viz.  that  substance  has  no  entitative  parts  before  the  coming 
of  quantity,  the  Thomists  argue  that,  if  it  had,  it  would  be 

1  Disputationes  Metaphysical,  Disp.  XL,  Sect.  4. 

3  Cursus  Phil.  Logica,  Pars.  II,  Q.  16,  A.  1  (ed.  Vives,  p.  466). 


58  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

formally  quantified,  for  to  have  entitative  parts  can  mean  no 
less  than  to  have  parts  which  are  situally  distinct,  i.e.  distinct 
with  respect  to  position,  or  order  of  the  parts  with  respect  to 
the  whole,  though  not  necessarily  with  regard  to  place,  that 
is  to  say,  with  regard  to  their  relation  to  surrounding 
bodies  ;  as  the  head  of  a  man  would  not  be  his  feet,  even 
though  they  were  not  supposed  to  have  different  relations  to 
surrounding  bodies.  To  have  parts  which  are  situally  dis- 
tinct, in  this  sense,  is  to  be  formally  quantified  ;  since  the 
proper  function  of  quantity  is  to  introduce  into  a  body  a 
merely  numerical  distinction  of  parts,  and  such  merely 
numerical  distinction  can  only  come  about  by  a  mere  dis- 
tinction of  the  parts  with  respect  to  their  position  with 
regard  to  the  whole.  It  follows,  then,  that  a  substance 
with  entitative  parts  would  be  formally  quantified,  which  is 
clearly  impossible  when  quantity  is  absent.  Thus  they 
contend  that  to  speak  of  parts  which  are  not  produced  by 
quantity  is  unintelligible.  In  fact,  it  seems  probable  that 
those  who  maintain  that  substance  has  parts  before  the 
coming  of  quantity,  are  really  making  use  of  an  awkward 
and  ambiguous  expression,  and  do  not  really  disagree  with 
those  who  deny  it.  For,  since  both  parties  agree  that  cor- 
poreal substance  is  composed  of  matter  and  form,  and  that 
matter  has  a  positive  capacity  or  potentiality  for  receiving 
quantity,  or  parts,  they  both  allow  that  it  is  not  simple,  in 
the  way  that  a  spiritual  substance  is,  which  is  absolutely 
indivisible.  To  say,  however,  of  a  substance  whose  divisi- 
bility consists  in  a  mere  passive  capacity  for  division,  and 
so  is  in  itself  undivided  and  indivisible,  that  it  has  parts, 
entitative  or  other,  is  clearly  an  awkward  and  ambiguous 
expression  ;  since  to  speak  in  this  way  implies  some  actual 
divisibility,  such  as  is  found  in  a  yard  of  cloth,  and  even 
division  ;  which  is  a  meaning  certainly  not  intended  by 
those  who  use  the  expression.  It  is  therefore  better  to  avoid 
it  and  say  that  substance  apart  from  quantity  has  no  parts, 
and  is  indivisible,  as  S.  Thomas  does.1 

1  Cf.  II  Sent.  dist.  Ill,  Q.  i,  a.  4  ;  and  Quodlibet,  IX,  a.  6. 


QUANTITY  59 

Question  II.     What  is  the  Nature  of  Quantity  in  Itself? 

The  question  we  have  just  reviewed,  on  the  distinction 
between  substance  and  quantity,  has,  of  course,  shown  us 
that  quantity  has  the  nature  of  accident,  and  the  latter  part 
of  it,  that  its  peculiar  nature,  as  distinguished  from  the  other 
accidents,  is  to  give  parts  to  substance.  We  now  have  to 
try  and  see  in  what  way  it  does  this  ;  and,  if  we  do  so,  we 
shall  have  arrived  at  its  definition,  since  all  accidents  must 
be  defined  by  means  of  the  effects  which  they  produce  on 
substance  ;  and  strictly  speaking  by  means  of  their  primary 
formal  effects,  i.e.  the  first  effects  which  they  naturally 
produce.  In  fact,  in  ordinary  affairs,  this  is  the  way  in  which 
we  judge  of  the  nature  of  accidents,  as  a  doctor  judges  the 
nature  of  a  disease  by  observing  the  effects  which  it  pro- 
duces in  his  patient — its  symptoms — and  we  are  here  trying 
to  find  the  peculiar  '  symptoms  '  of  quantity.  We  must  not, 
however,  suppose  that  its  nature  consists  in  the  actual  posit- 
ing of  this  effect ;  since,  in  common  with  all  other  accidents, 
it  is  that  which  is  naturally  fitted  to  be  in  some  subject,  not 
that  which  actually  is  in  it,  and  actually  affects  it.  For  the 
nature  of  a  thing  is  unaffected  whether  it  is  actually  existing 
or  not ;  whiteness  would  still  be  whiteness,  even  if  there 
were  none  left  in  the  world.  Since,  in  spite  of  this,  the  only 
means  we  have  of  judging  of  its  nature  is  by  observing  its 
actual  effects — for  we  have  no  intellectual  X-ray,  so  to 
speak,  by  which  we  can  penetrate  into  the  very  heart  of  it — 
it  is  these  which  we  must  examine.  What,  then,  are  its 
characteristic  effects  ? 

Consider  such  an  object  as  a  cube  of  sugar.  Since  it  is 
quantitatively  extended,  it  occupies  a  certain  three-dimen- 
sional portion  of  space.  This  extension  is  measurable  and 
also  divisible.  Since  the  cube  occupies  a  certain  portion  of 
space,  it  prevents  any  other  body  from  occupying  it,  i.e.  it 
is  impenetrable.  Now,  all  these  effects  presuppose  parts  in 
the  cube,  and  parts  which  are  not  coincident,  but  outside 
one  another,  and  in  a  certain  order  ;  this  being  an  essential 
condition  for  the  occupation  of  space.  Thus  we  have  seven 
characteristics  which  accompany  extended  quantity  in  a 


60  MODERN   THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

material  substance,  viz.  plurality  of  parts,  the  order  of  these 
parts  among  themselves,  their  capacity  for  filling  a  space, 
actual  occupation  of  a  space,  divisibility,  mensurability,  and 
impenetrability. 

We  want  to  discover  which  of  these  is  the  first  and  essen- 
tial characteristic  of  quantity  ;  and  it  is  not  easy  to  do  so, 
since  each  one  of  them  has  some  claim  to  be  so  considered. 
Thus,  John  of  S.  Thomas  holds  the  view  that  quantity  con- 
sists in  the  ordering  of  parts  among  themselves,  while  Suarez 
maintains  that  it  is  the  capacity  of  the  parts  for  filling  a 
place.  The  opinion  which  makes  the  primary  formal  effect 
of  quantity  to  be  impenetrability  is  reahy  the  same  as  this  : 
since  a  body  which  is  capable  of  filling  a  place  is  ipso  facto 
capable  of  excluding  another  body  from  the  same  place. 
Neither  of  these  views,  however,  can  be  maintained  if  we 
accept  what  was  said  above  as  to  the  absence  of  parts  in 
substance  before  the  coming  of  quantity,  since  to  unite  parts 
in  order,  and,  still  more  to  make  such  parts  capable  of  filling 
a  place,  presupposes  the  existence  of  such  parts. 

The  same  reason  rules  out  the  notion  that  mensurability  is 
the  nature  of  quantity,  an  opinion  said  to  have  been  held 
by  S.  Albert  the  Great ;  for,  in  order  that  a  thing  may  be 
measurable  by  an  extended  measure,  such  as  a  foot-rule,  it 
must  be  extended  in  itself,  i.e.  composed  of  parts  which  form 
a  continuous  body.  Scotus  is  said  to  have  thought  that  the 
nature  of  quantity  consisted  in  divisibility  ;  this,  however, 
could  not  be  true,  as  a  thing  is  divisible  because  it  is  quantita- 
tive, rather  than  quantitative  because  it  is  divisible. 

In  the  minds  of  all  Scholastics,  when  dealing  with  this 
question,  there  is  present  a  constant  theological  preoccupa- 
tion with  the  dogma  of  the  Eucharist ;  and  this  is  particu- 
larly evident  in  their  treatment  of  the  view  of  Durandus 
that  the  nature  of  quantity  consists  in  the  actual  occupation 
of  a  place  ;  in  connection  with  which  they  note  that,  since 
Christ's  body  in  the  Eucharist  does  not  occupy  a  place,  it 
would  be  necessary  to  deny  that  it  is  quantitative,  a  view 
which  they  stigmatise  as  at  least  erroneous  and  temerarious, 
if  not  heretical.  Apart  from  the  theological  reason,  it  is 
easy  to  see  that  the  actual  occupation  of  a  place  by  a  body 


QUANTITY  61 

is  a  consequence  of  its  being  extended,  and  having  parts  in 
itself,  and  that,  therefore,  such  occupation  cannot  be  the 
primary  formal  effect  of  quantity,  and  constitute  its  nature. 

Only  one  conception  of  its  nature  therefore  remains,  viz. 
that  it  consists  in  its  capacity  for  giving  to  substance  a 
plurality  of  parts,  in  doing  which  it  will  ipso  facto  put  them 
in  order  with  regard  to  the  whole  compound,  though  not 
necessarily  with  regard  to  place.  In  other  words,  the  parts 
will  be  situally  distinct,  though  not  necessarily  distinct 
locally.1  Some  writers,  as  Remer  and  Hoenen,  call  this 
effect  of  quantity  actual  extension  of  substance,  but  since 
this  expression  might  lead  to  confusion,  it  is  perhaps  better 
avoided  ;  though  the  view,  intended  to  be  expressed  by  it, 
is  that  now  generally  held  by  Thomists  ;  with  the  exception 
of  Gredt,  who  follows  John  of  S.  Thomas.2 

A  strong  presumption  in  favour  of  this  Thomist  view  is 
already  afforded  by  the  manifest  insufficiency  of  all  the  pro- 
posed alternatives,  and,  if  we  look  at  the  matter  directly,  we 
can  see  that  the  primary  formal  effect  of  quantity  must  be 
that  which  is  the  reason  and  source  of  all  the  other  properties 
or  effects,  which  may  proceed  from  it ;  for  this  is  what  we 
mean  by  primary  effect.  For  example,  if  we  were  enquiring 
what  was  the  primary  effect  of  alcohol  on  the  human  system, 
we  might  reply  it  is  the  deadening  of  the  nerve-cell  junctions 
(or  synapses,  as  they  are  called),  which,  in  turn,  causes 
resistance  to  the  passage  of  nervous  energy,  and  so  partial 
dissociation  of  the  brain  ;  causing,  in  its  turn,  loss  of  control 
of  the  emotions  by  the  intellect,  which  results  in  boisterous 
conduct  ;  and,  progressively,  loss  of  control  of  the  limbs  and 
sense  faculties,  eventually  ending  in  entire  suspension  of 

1  The  two  words  '  situs '  and  '  locus '  have  different  meanings  in  the 
Scholastic  vocabulary.  The  first  indicates  the  distinction  and  arrangement 
of  the  parts  of  a  body  among  themselves,  as  for  example  the  arrangement 
of  a  man's  limbs  in  sitting  or  standing  ;  whereas  the  word  '  place  '  implies 
a  relation  of  the  body  to  external  ones,  as  will  presently  be  explained  (cf . 
Chap.  VI,  pp.  78  ff.).  Of  course,  in  the  ordinary  way,  a  change  of  situs 
would  involve  a  change  of  location,  since  if  the  parts  of  a  body  are  differently 
arranged  among  themselves,  they  will  also  be  differently  arranged  with 
regard  to  surrounding  bodies  ;  but  this  need  not  happen,  as  we  shall 
shortly  see,  and  in  any  case  it  is  evident  that  situation  and  location  in 
the  Scholastic  sense  are  not  the  same. 

2  Gredt,  Elementa  Philosophies,  Sect.  315  (ed.  4,  1926). 


62  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

them,  in  a  heavy  sleep.1  All  these  latter  effects  result  from 
the  obstruction  of  the  synapses,  which,  therefore,  is  primary. 
We  are  asking  here,  not  only  what  is  the  primary  effect  of 
quantity,  but  what  is  its  primary  formal  effect,  and  that  will, 
evidently,  be  that  which  proceeds  from  quantity,  and  from 
no  other  accidental  form.  Now,  these  two  conditions  :  that 
the  effect  we  are  looking  for  must  be  the  source  of  all  other 
properties  proceeding  from  quantity  ;  and  that  by  which 
quantity  is  distinguished  from  any  other  form,  are  satisfied 
only  in  the  case  of  that  effect  of  quantity  which  is  the  giving 
to  substance  a  plurality  of  parts,  on  which  follows,  immedi- 
ately, their  order  with  respect  to  the  whole  ;  for  it  is  clear 
that  no  other  accident  gives  substance  a  plurality  of  ordered 
parts,  and  so  this  property  is  distinctive  of  quantity,  or 
formal ;  and,  moreover,  it  is  primary,  since,  as  we  saw  above, 
the  other  properties  of  quantity,  viz.  capacity  for  filling  a 
place,  divisibility,  mensurability  and  impenetrability  follow, 
once  the  substance  has  been  given  such  a  plurality  of  parts, 
and  presuppose  it.  Thus  it  is  evidently  the  primary  formal 
effect  of  quantity. 

The  difficulty  of  this  view  is,  no  doubt,  chiefly  to  be  found 
in  the  fact  that  we  cannot  imagine  a  thing  with  parts  which 
are  numerically  distinct  one  from  another,  and  yet,  not  dis- 
tinct as  regards  place.  Undoubtedly,  a  body  which  has  such 
parts,  which  are  outside  one  another  as  regards  itself,  is  ipso 
facto  in  a  state  which  makes  it  able  to  fill  a  place  ;  but  in 
order  that  it  may  actually  do  so,  two  further  conditions  are 
required  :  (i)  that  there  actually  exist  other  bodies  which 
constitute  the  place,  and  (2)  that  their  internal  dimensions 
be  actually  applied  to  the  external  dimensions  of  the  body 
which  is  to  be  in  place.  For  it  must  be  borne  in  mind  that 
the  state  of  being  in  a  place  arises,  not  from  something 
internal  to  a  body,  but  from  something  extrinsic  to  it,  viz. 
the  proximity  and  juxtaposition  of  other  bodies.  Hence,  if 
either  of  the  conditions,  mentioned  above,  is  not  fulfilled, 
the  body  will  be  extended  in  itself,  and  yet  not  be  in  any 
place.  So,  if  we  suppose  that  there  existed  only  one  body,  it 
could  not  be  in  place,  since,  owing  to  the  absence  of  all  others 

1  Cf.  McDougall,  Abnormal  Psychology,  pp.  67-74. 


QUANTITY  63 

which  might  surround  it,  the  extrinsic  relation  of  being 
situated  with  respect  to  them,  i.e.  of  being  in  place,  could 
not  arise.  Similarly,  if  a  body,  which  was  one  of  many, 
were  yet  not  related  to  them  by  means  of  its  extension,  they 
would  not  surround  it  by  means  of  extension,  and  so  it  would 
not  fill  the  extended  place  which  they  form.  The  difficulty, 
therefore,  is  due  to  the  imagination,  for  we  cannot  imagine 
one  body  joined  to  another  by  any  other  means  than  by  the 
application  of  the  extension  of  the  one  to  that  of  the  other, 
since  this  is  the  only  union  of  which  the  senses  tell  us.  We 
can,  however,  understand  that  there  is  nothing  necessary 
about  this  particular  mode  of  union,  since  it  is  not  necessary 
that  the  extension  of  a  body  should  have  any  relation  to  the 
extension  of  others,  if  it  is  present  to  them  in  some  other  way. 
It  is  also  extremely  clear  from  the  consideration  of  the 
unique  body  (the  only  one  in  the  world),  that  for  a  body  to 
be  actually  in  place  is  a  condition  totally  distinct  from  that 
of  being  extended  in  itself. 

If,  then,  as  is  certainly  the  case,  to  be  in  place  and  to  fill 
a  place  is  an  extrinsic  relation  added  to  the  nature  of  extended 
body,  it  follows  that  the  exclusion  of  another  body  from  a 
place  already  occupied,  is,  though  a  natural  consequence  of 
such  occupation,  as  experience  shows,  nevertheless  not  a 
necessary  formal  effect  of  extension  or  quantity.  This  is 
another  way  of  saying  that  such  impenetrability  is  not  of 
the  very  nature  of  extended  or  quantified  body,  and  it  is 
possible  to  have  an  extended  thing  which  is  not  im- 
penetrable. 

From  our  conclusions  as  to  the  relationship  of  substance 
and  quantity,  certain  other  results  also  follow.  First,  tha 
since  quantity  is  not  of  the  essence  of  material  substance, 
absolutely  speaking,  it  would  be  possible  to  have  such  sub- 
stance without  any  quantity,  since  we  can  take  away  from  a 
thing  some  attribute  which  does  not  belong  to  its  nature, 
without  destroying  that  nature.  Substance,  however,  in 
this  case,  would  still  retain  its  natural  requirement  to  be 
quantified,  and,  in  certain  cases,  it  is  impossible  to  conceive 
of  an  unquantified,  i.e.  unextended  material  substance,  as  in 
the  case  of  living  things  which  must  be  organised,  i.e.  have 


64  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

parts,  in  order  to  live.  If  quantity  were  removed  from 
material  substance  in  this  way,  the  body  would  not  be  reduced 
to  a  point,  as  some  have  supposed,  but  would  simply  have  no 
relation  to  extension  ;  whereas  a  point  is  the  beginning  of  an 
extension. 

A  more  difficult  question  arises  when  we  come  to  consider 
the  possibility  of  the  existence  of  quantity  divorced  from 
substance,  for  though  we  might  summarily  assert  that  it  can 
so  exist,  in  common  with  all  other  accidents  (since  an 
accident  requires  substance  only  for  its  support,  and  con- 
sequently if  supported,  in  some  other  way,  can  dispense 
with  it),  yet  certain  difficulties  peculiar  to  quantity  remain. 
For  quantity  immediately  affects  material  substance,  and 
indeed  results  from  the  nature  of  matter.1  We  must,  by  all 
means,  avoid  thinking  of  material  substance  as  something 
inert  and  passive,  on  which  quantity  is  imposed  from  without, 
like  a  coat  of  whitewash  on  a  wall.  On  the  contrary,  quan- 
tity, like  the  qualities  of  bodies,  grows,  as  it  were,  from  them  ; 
as  a  plant  grows  from  the  ground,  being  enabled  to  do  so  by 
the  nature  of  the  soil.  It  seems,  then,  that  the  whole  raison 
d'etre  of  quantity  is  to  produce  extension  in  substance,  and 
consequently  it  cannot  exist  if  it  does  not  do  so,  which  would 
be  the  case  if  it  were  separated  from  substance.  Now,  as  we 
saw,  the  primary  function  of  quantity  is  to  give  extension  to 
substance,  but  in  order  to  do  this,  it  must  be  extended  in 
itself.  This  accidental  extension,  therefore,  is  its  true  nature, 
and  it  may  still  have  a  function  to  fulfil  even  if  deprived  of  its 
primary  one. 

In  order  to  bring  out  the  meaning  of  the  statement  that 
quantity  can  preserve  its  nature,  and  a  certain  function,  even 
if  deprived  of  the  possibility  of  exercising  its  primary  function 
owing  to  the  absence  of  substance,  we  may,  perhaps,  be 
allowed  to  make  use  of  an  illustration,  though  it  is  not  to  be 
supposed  that  the  two  cases  are  parallel.  The  primary 
function  of  a  doctor  is  to  cure  the  sick,  and  in  order  to  do 
this  he  must  be  versed  in  the  medical  sciences.  Now,  suppose 
he  were  in  some  '  brave  new  world  '  where  there  were  no  sick 
people  to  cure,  he  would  still  continue  to  be  a  doctor  so  long 

1  Cf.  Summa  Theol.,  Pars  I,  Q.  77,  a.  6.,  o.  et  ad  lum  et  311m. 


QUANTITY  65 

as  his  scientific  competence  remained  ;  and  he  would  also 
have  a  function  to  fulfil,  though  not  his  primary  one,  in  so 
far  as  he  assisted  the  people  to  preserve  their  health,  or  even 
to  get  healthier  and  healthier.  Just  as  quantity  cannot 
quantify  substance  if  there  is  no  substance,  so  the  doctor 
cannot  cure  disease  if  there  is  none,  but  quantity  preserves 
its  nature  of  accidental  extension,  and  the  doctor  his  of 
medical  scientist,  and  both  fulfil  a  derivative  function  ; 
quantity,  in  virtue  of  its  own  essential  extension,  giving 
extension  to  other  accidents,  and  the  doctor,  in  virtue  of  his 
medical  knowledge,  preserving  the  health  of  the  healthy  ; 
prevention,  in  his  case,  being  the  substitute  for  cure.  If, 
then,  we  imagine  a  case  in  which  it  was  necessary  that  the 
accidents  of  some  substance  should  remain  and  be  known, 
when  the  substance  had  disappeared,  quantity  would  still 
have  a  necessary  role  to  fill,  viz.  to  make  them  extended, 
impenetrable,  and  so  on.  Hence,  it  would  still  have  a  reason 
of  being.  If  it  be  further  objected  that  quantity  detached 
from  its  subject  will  not  be  any  particular  quantity,  since  it 
is  not  the  quantity  of  anything  ;  and  that,  therefore,  it  is 
impossible  to  conceive  of  it  as  existing,  since  only  concrete 
singular  things  exist  ;  we  notice  that  quantity  is  peculiar, 
among  the  accidents,  inasmuch  as  it  is  by  quantity  that  things 
are  distinguished  as  numerically  different,  i.e.  as  individuals.1 
Unlike  qualities,  such  as  colour,  say  the  colour  white,  which, 
if  abstracted  from  its  subject,  would  give  us  whiteness,  not 
this  white  thing ;  quantity,  even  in  abstraction,  is  of  a  certain 
definite  amount,  since  its  extension  is  proper  to  itself,  and 
does  not  depend  on  its  subject,  whereas  whiteness,  and  such- 
like qualities,  are  only  made  individual,  particular  and 
definite  by  being  the  whiteness,  and  so  on,  of  a  particular 
subject. 

Quantity,  then,  in  our  hypothetical  case,  could  exist 
without  its  subject,  since  it  would  retain  its  definiteness  and 
individuality,  and  have  a  function  to  perform,  even  though 
deprived  of  its  primary  one. 

1  Cf.  Remer,  Cosmologia  (editio  sexta),  p.  143,  Resp.  ad  2am  diff. 
Summa  Theologica,  Pars  III,  Q.  77,  a.  2  ;  IV  Sent.  dist.  XII,  Q.  I,  a.  I, 
Sol.  3,  ad  2um,  et  ad  311m  ;   V.  Metaphysica,  Lect.  15. 


66  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

These  considerations  throw  a  little  more  light  on 
the  difficult  question  of  the  nature  of  quantity,  and, 
of  course,  have  their  special  application  in  theo- 
logy, in  the  question  relating  to  the  Eucharistic 
accidents. 


CHAPTER  V 

THE   CONTINUUM 

Notion  of  Continuity — Zeno's  Arguments — The  Divisibility  of  the 
Continuum — Is  it  Composed  of  Indivisible  Elements  ? — Is  it 
Infinitely  Divisible  ? — The  Parts  of  the  Continuum — The 
Indivisibles  of  the  Continuum — Solution  of  Zeno's  Arguments. 

We  have  already  noticed,  what  is  indeed  obvious,  that  there 
are  two  kinds  of  quantity,  continuous  and  discrete,  of  which 
continuous  quantity  is  a  primary  kind,  while  discrete  is  a 
derivative  of  it.  It  is,  therefore,  a  natural  sequence  to  pass 
from  the  consideration  of  quantity  in  general  to  that  of  con- 
tinuous quantity.  No  doubt,  the  analysis  of  continuous 
quantity,  or  the  continuum,  was  first  suggested  by  observa- 
tion of  the  material  world,  since  bodies  are,  at  least  in  appear- 
ance, continuous.  The  philosophical  discussion  of  it,  how- 
ever, leads  us  into  a  region  more  abstract  than  that  of  natural 
philosophy ;  and  indeed  this  section,  like  the  preceding, 
really  forms  part  of  the  science  of  mathematical  philosophy. 
What,  then,  is  the  essential  feature  of  continuity  ?  To 
answer  this  question  we  notice  in  the  first  place  the  distinc- 
tion which  exists,  and  which  Aristotle  points  out,  between 
the  continuous  and  the  contiguous  ;  for  two  things,  or  two 
parts  of  the  same  thing,  are  continuous,  if  the  extremities  in 
which  they  join  are  the  same  ;  and  contiguous,  if  their 
extremities  are  together,  i.e.  in  the  same  immediate  place. 
They  are  then  said  to  be  in  contact.1  Thus  the  continuum 
is  a  reality  which  is  actually  one  in  extension,  stretching  out 
without  any  intervals,  e.g.  a  geometrical  line.  So,  to  consti- 
tute the  continuum  mere  juxtaposition  is  insufficient,  the 
parts  must  be  united  by  a  common  term.    As  we  consider,  by 

1  Aristotle,  Physics,  226b34,  227a27,  23ia2i,  io68b26,  1069*14  ;  and 
S.  Thomas  in  V  Phys.,  Lect.  5  ;  VI  Phys.,  Lect.  1  ;  in  XI  Met.,  Lect.  13, 
ed.  Cathala,  n.  2404-15. 

F  67 


68  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

abstraction,  one,  two,  or  three  dimensions,  we  arrive  at 
three  species  of  continuum  :  the  line,  the  surface,  and  the 
volume  (cube  or  solid).  In  the  line  points  are  in  some  way 
present.  Since  the  point  is  indivisible,  points  are  called  the 
indivisibles  of  a  line.  Both  lines  and  surfaces  are  indivisible 
in  some  respect,  the  line,  namely,  with  respect  to  breadth  and 
depth,  the  surface,  with  respect  to  depth  only.  Thus  lines 
are  said  to  be  the  indivisibles  of  surfaces,  surfaces  of  solids. 

It  is  advisable  to  notice  here  that  there  are  two  genera  of 
continuum,  viz.  the  permanent  and  successive.  The  first  is, 
again,  of  two  kinds,  the  physical  continuum,  which  is  natural 
body  ;  and  the  mathematical,  whose  species,  solid,  surface, 
and  line,  we  have  just  enumerated.  The  successive  con- 
tinuum is  of  two  kinds  :   motion  and  time. 

If  we  now  examine  this  notion  of  the  continuum  as 
uninterrupted  extension,  it  seems  that  since  it  is  an  extension 
it  is  divisible  without  end,  in  which  case  it  appears  that  we 
might  have  an  actually  infinite  multitude,  an  hypothesis 
which  few  accept,  and  which  presents  grave  difficulties. 
(Cf.  pp.  107  ff.)  If,  on  the  other  hand,  the  continuum  is  not 
infinitely  divisible,  we  must  come  finally  to  indivisibles,  so 
that  in  the  last  resort  the  divisible  continuum  will  be  com- 
posed of  indivisibles,  the  extended  of  the  unextended.  This 
difficulty  was  first  recognised,  though  obscurely,  by  Zeno, 
who  argued  on  the  assumption  that  the  continuum  is  com- 
posed of  indivisibles,  and  so  constructed  his  famous  proofs  of 
the  impossibility  of  motion,  which  have  been  referred  to  in 
our  Introduction  (p.  7).  Though  one  of  these,  the  Achilles, 
may  be  invalidated  by  his  '  ignorance  of  the  theory  of  infinite 
convergent  numerical  series,'  as  Whitehead  suggests,1  the 
others  are  unassailable,  if  we  admit  his  premise  ;  but  they 
stand  or  fall  with  it.  Thus  if  we  prove  that  the  continuum 
is  not  composed  only  of  indivisibles,  we  shall  ipso  facto  refute 
these  arguments.2    They  are  as  follows  : 

1.  The  Dichotomy.  In  order  to  travel  a  distance,  a  body 
must  first  travel  half  the  distance  :    and  half  the  distance 

1  Process  and  Reality ,  p.  95.  The  suggestion  was  first  made  by  Descartes. 
Vide  CEuvres  (Adam  and  Tannery),  Tom.  IV,  p.  445. 

2  Aristotle,  Physics,  239^11-^30  ;    S.  Thomas  in  VI  Phys.,  Lect    11.  ■ 


THE  CONTINUUM  69 

remains  to  be  travelled.  Again,  since  the  first  half  is  divis- 
ible, it  must  first  travel  half  of  that  half,  and  so  to  infinity, 
since  a  magnitude  is  divisible  to  infinity.  Infinities,  how- 
ever, cannot  be  traversed  in  a  finite  time,  therefore  the  body 
will  never  arrive,  nor  even  can  it  move  from  one  place  to 
another. 

2.  The  Achilles.  Achilles  and  the  tortoise  run  a  race.  If 
the  tortoise  is  given  a  start,  Achilles  can  never  catch  it  up. 
For,  first  he  must  run  to  the  place  from  which  the  tortoise 
started.  When  he  gets  there,  the  tortoise  will  have  gone  to  a 
point  further  on.  Achilles  must  then  run  to  that  point,  and 
the  tortoise  will  have  gone  still  further.  This  will  go  on  for 
ever,  the  tortoise  always  being  ahead,  so  that  Achilles  will 
never  catch  him  up.  Since  this  seems  absurd,  it  is  better  to 
say  that  nothing  moves.  (Aristotle  and  S.  Thomas  omit  the 
picturesque  details.) 

3.  The  Arrow.  Everything  which  is  in  a  place  either 
moves  or  is  at  rest.  Now  an  arrow  in  its  flight  would,  at  each 
moment  of  it,  be  in  its  place  :  therefore  at  each  moment  it 
would  either  move  or  be  at  rest.  But  it  cannot  move,  for 
then  it  would  not  be  in  one  place,  but  in  two.  Therefore  it  is 
at  rest.  If,  therefore,  it  moves  at  no  moment,  it  does  not 
move  in  the  whole  time,  and  so  is  at  rest. 

There  is  also  a  fourth  argument  called  the  Road.  Strictly 
speaking,  only  the  first  two  concern  us  here  ;  and  both 
assume  that  the  continuum  is  actually  composed  of  indivis- 
ibles.   We  will  therefore  first  consider  this  question. 

Section  I.     On  the  Divisibility  of  the  Continuum. 

Question  I.  Is  the  Continuum  Composed  of  Indivisible 
Elements  ? 
That  it  is  not,  is  admitted  by  all  philosophers  of  all  schools, 
with  the  possible  exception  of  the  Pythagoreans,  and  some 
Scholastics  of  the  seventeenth  century  ;  for  it  is,  in  fact, 
very  obvious  that  it  cannot  be  so  composed.  Clearly  the 
indivisibles,  inasmuch  as  they  are  indivisibles,  are  unextended. 
An  extended  continuum,  however,  cannot  be  composed  of 
unextended  elements.    Moreover,  such  elements  would  either 


70  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

be  at  a  distance  from  one  another,  in  which  case  they  would 
not  form  a  continuum,  or  in  contact,  in  which  case  they  would 
be  coincident ;  since,  having  no  extremes  nor  middles,  they 
must  touch  in  their  totality  if  at  all.  So,  again,  they  would 
not  form  an  extended  continuum,  whose  parts  must  be  out- 
side one  another.  In  other  words,  if  we  suppose  that  an 
extended  continuum  is  composed  of  indivisibles  which  are 
outside  one  another,  continuity  disappears,  and  if  they  are 
not  outside  one  another,  extension  disappears,  so  that  in 
neither  case  can  the  continuum  be  composed  of  indivisibles. 

It  is  useless  to  suggest  that  the  indivisibles  are  infinitely 
small :  for  though,  in  Mathematics,  we  may  speak  of  an 
innitely  small  quantity,  we  mean  a  quantity  whose  magni- 
tude is  indeterminable.  That  such  quantities  cannot  be 
infinitely  small,  in  the  philosophic  sense,  is  clear  from  the 
fact  that  they  are  not  nothing,  and  so  must  have  a  finite 
magnitude,  though  an  indefinitely  small  one.  That  they 
have  such  a  magnitude  is  seen  from  the  fact  that  they  can  be 
further  divided,  which  in  itself  disallows  the  suggestion  that 
the  indivisibles  are  of  this  kind. 

Further,  the  very  impossibilities  which  result  from  Zeno's 
arguments  confirm  our  contention  that  his  hypothesis,  viz. 
that  the  continuum  is  composed  of  indivisibles,  is  false  ;  for, 
if  it  were  true,  the  slowest  and  quickest  movers  would  move 
at  the  same  speed  :  since  the  quickest  could  not  pass  over 
more  than  one  indivisible  element  of  space  in  less  than 
one  indivisible  element  of  time,  i.e.  in  less  than  one  instant, 
since  by  hypothesis  an  instant  is  the  least  time  there  is, 
otherwise  it  would  be  divisible  :  nor  could  the  slowest  take 
more  than  a  single  instant  to  pass  over  less  than  one  indivis- 
ible element  of  space,  since  this  is,  by  hypothesis,  the  least 
space.  Consequently,  they  would  both  pass  over  one 
indivisible  element  of  space  in  the  same  time,  viz.  one  instant, 
and  so  would  travel  at  the  same  rate. 

Question  II.     Is  the  Continuum  Infinitely  Divisible?' 

This  conclusion,  that  the  continuum  is  not  composed  of 
indivisibles,  carries  with  it  an  important  corollary  :  for  if  we 
never  come  to  ultimate  indivisible  elements  when  we  divide 


THE  CONTINUUM  71 

the  continuum,  it  must  be  divisible  to  infinity.  Now,  just  as 
philosophers  are  practically  unanimous  in  asserting  that  the 
continuum  is  not  composed  of  indivisibles,  so  they  also  agree 
that  it  is  divisible  to  infinity.  It  is  as  well  to  recall  here  the 
distinction  between  the  continuum  formally  considered, 
i.e.  as  it  is  one  real  extension — the  mathematical  continuum, 
and  the  physical  or  material  continuum,  viz.  the  actual 
bodies  in  the  universe,  which  are  extended  and  endowed 
with  a  variety  of  accidents.  Those  who  consider  the  physical 
continuum  only,  hold  that  it  is  not  infinitely  divisible  :  and 
this  we  do  not  deny,  but  rather  affirm  with  S.  Thomas  :  for 
the  mathematical  or  abstract  continuum  is  divided  into 
proportional  parts,  i.e.  parts  which  are  some  proportion  of 
the  whole,  as  halves  or  thirds,  which  can  again  be  divided 
into  halves  or  thirds  ;  and  it  is  clear  that  we  can  go  on  for 
ever  taking  a  half  of  half,  or  a  third  of  a  third,  and  so  on,  so 
that  this  continuum  is  infinitely  divisible.  A  priori  we  can 
see  that  this  may  not  be  true  of  the  physical  continuum, 
and  experience  shows  that,  in  fact,  it  is  not :  for  the  physical 
continuum  is  composed  of  what  are  known  as  aliquot  parts, 
determined  ones,  namely,  which  when  added  together  make 
up  the  whole.  These  have  a  determinate  extension,  and  so 
cannot  be  further  divided.  The  reason  of  this  is  that  in  the 
physical  continuum  we  come  to  a  minimum  quantity  of 
matter  which  is  necessary  to  support  a  given  form,  such 
minima,  for  example,  as  the  molecule  or  atom  would  be. 
Now,  if  this  minimum  be  further  divided  we  get  a  body  of  a 
different  nature,  i.e.  the  original  form  disappears,  and  another 
takes  its  place.  So  S.  Thomas  says  :  '  Corpus  mathematicum 
est  divisible  in  infinitum,  in  quo  consider atur  sola  ratio  quanti- 
tatis  in  qua  nihil  est  repugnans  divisioni  infinites.  Sed  corpus 
naturale,  quod  consideratur  sub  tota  forma,  non  potest  in 
infinitum  dividi,  quia,  quando  jam  ad  minimum  deducitur, 
statim  propter  debilitatem  virtutis  convertitur  in  aliud.  Unde 
est  invenire  minimam  carnem,  sicut  dicitur  in  I.  Physicorum, 
nee  tamen  corpus  naturale  componitur  ex  mathematicis.'1 

1  De  Sensu  et  Sensato,  Lect.  15.  Cf.  Summa  Theol.,  Pars  I,  Q.  48, 
a.  4,  ad  3um  ;  I.  II.,  Q.  85,  a.  2.0  ;  II  Sent.  dist.  XXX,  Q.  2,  a.  2.0  ; 
III  Phys.,  Lect.  10,  a.  9  ;  de  Potentia  IV,  a.  1,  ad  5um  ;  IV  Sent.  dist. 
XII,  Q.  1,  a.  2,  Sol.  3. 


72  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

Thus  in  the  physical  continuum  we  come  to  ultimate  parts 
which  cannot  be  further  divided  ;  so  that  this  continuum  is 
not  infinitely  divisible.  This  seems  to  be  what  Fr.  Leslie 
Walker  suggests,  though  he  charges  Aristotle  with  denying 
it  :  and  what  is  worse,  with  being  '  led  astray  by  appear- 
ances.'1 Thus  with  regard  to  the  abstract  or  mathematical 
continuum,  which  alone  concerns  us  here,  there  seem  to  be 
few  or  no  philosophers  who  do  not  allow  that  it  is  divisible 
to  infinity. 

That  it  is  so,  is  seen  from  what  was  said  above,  for  we  can 
go  on  for  ever  taking  a  half  of  a  half,  and  so  on.  Moreover,  it 
is  clear  that  the  whole  continuum  can  be  divided,  being  an 
extension,  and  the  quotient  will  be  an  extension  and  so 
divisible,  and  the  same  will  hold  good  in  all  further  divisions, 
so  that  no  end  can  be  put  to  them.2 

Section  II.     The  Parts  of  the  Continuum. 

If,  then,  the  continuum  is  not  composed  of  indivisibles,  it 
must  be  composed  of  divisibles,  i.e.  of  extended  parts,  such 
as  halves,  quarters,  etc.  The  name  '  parts  '  is  applied 
exclusively  to  such  extended  portions,  and  not  to  the 
indivisibles.  Since,  then,  such  parts  exist  in  the  continuum, 
they  may  exist  there  either  actually  or  potentially,  i.e.  in 
such  a  way  that  they  can  be  made  actual  parts  by  division. 
There  are,  therefore,  two  main  views  corresponding  to  these 
two  possibilities,  while  some  have  tried  to  reconcile  them. 

Thus  :  A.  (i)  Many  teach  that  the  parts  exist  in  act. 
Plato  held  this  view,  according  to  Prof.  Ross,  who  agrees 
with  him  and  adds  :  '  to  cut  a.  ball  in  two  is  not  to  bring  into 
existence  the  common  plane  of  its  halves,  it  is  to  drive  your 
knife  along  a  plane  that  is  already  there.'3  Similarly,  John 
of  S.  Thomas,  Goudin,  and  Gredt.  These  maintain  the 
actual  existence  of  parts  without  any  reservation. 
■  (2)  Others  say  that  though  the  parts  are  not  actually 
divided,  yet  they  are  actually  distinct  :  existing  formally  as 
parts  joined  together  by  continuing  indivisibles.  So,  Suarez, 
and  others. 

1  Aristotelean  Society's  Proceedings,  1922-3,  pp.  98-9. 

2  Cf.  Leibniz,  Ep.  ad  P.  des  Bosses. 

*  Ross,  Aristotle's  Metaphysics,  Vol.  I,  Introd.,  p.  lv. 


THE  CONTINUUM  73 

B.  Many  others,  however,  teach  that  the  parts  exist  only 
potentially  in  the  continuum  :  inasmuch  as  there  are  in  it 
no  actual  limits,  which  serve  to  separate  one  part  from 
another.  This  is  the  view  of  Aristotle,  as  can  be  seen  in 
VII  Met.,  I039a3  ff.  '  The  double  line  consists  of  two  halves 
— potentially  :  for  the  actualisation  of  the  halves  divides 
them  from  one  another.'  S.  Thomas  agrees,  as  in  his  com- 
ment on  this  passage  (Lect.  13)  ;  also  in  Lect.  16,  and  Bk.  V, 
Lect.  21  :  '  Partes  sunt  in  potentia  in  toto  continuo  '  ;  and 
VII  Phys.,  Lect.  9  :  '  Pars  auteni  prout  est  in  toto,  non  est 
divisa  in  actu,  sect  in  potentia  tantum  ' ;  and  IV.  Sent.  dist.  X, 
Q.  1,  a.  3,  qa4,  sol.  3  ad  ium.  :  '  Partes  alicujus  homogenei 
continui  ante  divisionem  non  habent  esse  actu  sed  potentia 
tantum,'  and  many  other  places.1 

C.  Some  try  to  reconcile  these  two  views,  saying  that 
though  the  parts  are  not  actually  in  the  continuum  con- 
sidered formally  as  parts,  yet  considered  as  realities  they 
are  actual  in  it.    So  Donat,  and  Hugon. 

The  argument  which  Aristotle  and  S.  Thomas  use  to  prove 
their  opinion  is  of  extreme  simplicity  and  clarity.  The  first, 
and  most  essential  characteristic  of  the  continuum  as  a 
species  of  quantity  is  its  unity.  If  the  continuum  were  not 
essentially  one,  we  should  have,  not  continuous,  but  discrete, 
quantity.  This  being  so,  it  is  impossible  that  the  parts 
should  be  actual,  since  the  least  that  this  could  mean  would 
be  that  they  are  already  actual  entities,  and  so  actual 
unities.  A  number  of  such  unities,  however,  even  if  in  juxta- 
position, could  never  constitute  an  entity  which  was  essen- 
tially one.  It  may  be  useful  to  quote  the  very  words  of 
S.  Thomas,2  which  are  lucidity  itself  :  '  Sicut  aliquid  est  ens, 
sicut  et  unum  :  unum  autem  est  quod  est  in  se  indivisum  et  ab 
aliis  divisum  :  pars  autem  prout  est  in  toto,  non  est  divisa  in 
actu  sed  in  potentia  tantum,  unde  non  est  actu  ens  neque  una, 
sed  in  potentia  tantum.'  So  we  may  express  this  simple  truth 
by  saying  that  if  the  parts  are  actual  entities,  they  will  be 
actually  many,  and  so  cannot  at  the  same  time  be  actually 
one,  or  a  continuum. 

1  I  de  Ccelo,  Lect.  3,  Sect.  6  ;  I  Phya.  Lect.  9.  Sect.  8  ;  Summa  Theol., 
III  Pars,  Q.  76,  a.  3,  ad  ium  ;  I  Pars,  Q.  85,  a.  8,  ad  2um  ;  Quodlibet  I, 
a.  21.  2  VII  Phys.,  Lect.  9,  Sec.  5. 


74  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

It  is  worth  noting  that  those  who  take  the  middle  view 
contend  that  the  matter  of  which  the  parts  are  composed  is 
actually  present  in  the  continuum  before  division,  which 
nobody  denies  ;  consequently,  their  effort  at  reconciliation 
is  unsuccessful,  for  they  do  not,  by  this  means,  solve  the 
question,  which  is  whether  the  parts  considered  formally  as 
distinct  entities  are  actual  before  division.  Since,  however, 
they  deny  that  they  are  actual,  their  opinion  seems  to  be 
that  of  S.  Thomas,  and  the  distinction  introduced  by  them 
only  serves  to  obscure  the  real  nature  of  the  dispute.  A 
confirmatory  argument  in  favour  of  this  same  view  is  derived 
from  the  infinite  divisibility  of  the  continuum,  since  if  the 
parts  were  actually  present  in  the  continuum,  they  would 
have  to  be  either  infinite  or  finite  in  number.  They  cannot, 
however,  be  either  ;  for  if  they  were  infinite  in  number  we 
should  have  an  actually  infinite  multitude  in  the  genus  of 
quantity,  which,  as  we  shall  see,  is  impossible  ;  and,  more- 
over, they  would  not  be  parts  but  indivisible  points,  since,  if 
they  had  any  extension,  however  small,  when  they  were 
multiplied  an  infinity  of  times,  they  would  constitute  an 
infinite  magnitude  :  so  that  any  body,  even  the  smallest, 
would  have  an  infinite  magnitude,  which  is  absurd.  Now  we 
have  proved,  and  Suarez  agrees,  that  the  continuum  is  not 
constituted  of  indivisibles.  So,  it  is  impossible  that  the  parts 
should  be  infinite  in  number.  Nor  can  their  number  be  finite, 
for,  in  this  case,  the  continuum  would  not  be  divisible  to 
infinity,  which  we  have  seen  that  it  is.  Hence,  it  is  imposs- 
ible that  the  continuum  should  be  composed  of  actual  parts. 

Section  III.     The  Indivisibles  of  the  Continuum. 

In  order  to  complete  our  analysis  of  the  nature  of  the  con- 
tinuum, something  must  be  added  as  to  the  other  elements 
which  are  conceived  of  as  being  in  it,  in  addition  to  its  parts, 
viz.  the  indivisibles.  Now,  these  indivisibles  are  of  two 
kinds,  the  terminating  indivisibles  which  are  thought  of  as 
actually  limiting  the  continuum,  such  as  the  points  at  the 
end  of  a  line ;  and  the  continuing  indivisibles  which  are 
thought  of  as  being  within  the  continuum,  and  joining 
together  the  parts  which  can  be  separated  at  them.    We  ask, 


THE  CONTINUUM  75 

then,  whether  indivisibles  of  these  two  kinds  are  actually,  or 
only  potentially,  present  in  the  continuum. 

1.  There  can  be  little  doubt  that  the  terminating  indivisibles 
are  actual,  since,  if  the  continuum  is  limited  at  all,  it  must 
be  by  means  of  an  actual  limit.  There  is,  however,  difference 
of  opinion  as  to  the  nature  of  this  limit,  for  some  regard  it  as  a 
mere  negation,  the  negation,  that  is,  of  further  extension, 
while  others  think  that  it  is  a  positive  reality,  being  the  reality 
of  the  limited  body,  in  so  far  as  this  connotes  the  negation  of 
further  extension.  A  much  more  general  view,  however,  is 
that  they  are  something  positive,  really  distinct  from  the 
continuum  which  they  terminate,  the  distinction,  of  course, 
not  being  that  of  one  quantitative  thing  from  another,  but  of 
the  determinator  from  the  determinated,  and  so  a  modal  dis- 
tinction, i.e.  that  which  obtains  between  an  entity  and  some 
mode  of  it.  This  seems,  on  the  whole,  to  be  the  most  prob- 
able opinion,  though  since  all  agree  that  the  terminating 
indivisibles  are  actually  present,  for  the  reason  given  above, 
the  question  is  one  of  lesser  importance.  The  reason  for 
saying  that  they  are  positive  realities  is  that  where  a  con- 
tinuum begins  there  is  something  real  and  positive  which 
was  not  present  before,  and  where  it  ends  something  positive 
and  real  ceases.  Consequently,  the  terminating  indivisibles 
being  the  beginning  and  end  of  the  continuum,  they  must  be 
something  positive  and  real.  For  contact  too,  it  is  necessary 
that  bodies  should  touch  by  means  of  indivisibles,  otherwise 
they  would  interpenetrate.  They  cannot,  however,  touch  in 
a  negation,  for  to  do  so  would  be,  in  fact,  not  to  touch,  and 
since  the  contact  is  to  be  real,  the  indivisibles  must  be  real 
also.  Further,  they  must  be  distinct  from  the  continuum 
itself,  since  this  is  divisible,  and  they  are  indivisible. 

2.  With  regard  to  the  continuing  indivisibles,  the  Nomin- 
alists hold  them  to  be  a  mental  fiction,  while  some  sixteenth 
and  seventeenth  century  writers,  such  as  John  of  S.  Thomas, 
whose  opinion  in  recent  times  has  been  espoused  by  others,  as 
Gredt,  think  that  they  exist  in  act,  and  are  really  distinct 
from  the  parts  which  they  unite.  There  is  little  doubt  that 
neither  of  these  views  accords  with  that  of  Aristotle  and 
S.  Thomas,  for  it  seems  clear  that  these  considered  that  they 


76  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

do  not  exist  in  act,  but  only  potentially.  It  is,  indeed,  only 
another  way  of  saying  that  the  parts  of  the  continuum  are 
potential  only,  and  not  actual,  since  it  is  clear  that  if  the 
continuing  indivisibles  were  actual,  they  would  actually 
determine  the  parts,  and  make  them  actual.  So,  if  the  parts 
are  not  actual,  as  we  have  already  seen  to  be  the  case, 
neither  are  the  continuing  indivisibles. 

Section  IV.     The  Arguments  of  Zeno. 

We  are  now  in  a  position  to  see  what  answer  can  be  made 
to  the  arguments  of  Zeno,  against  the  possibility  of  motion. 
In  effect,  Zeno  argues  :  You  rnaintain  that  the  continuum  is 
infinitely  divisible.  Now,  the  only  things  of  which  there  can 
be  an  infinity  in  a  lineal  continuum  are  points,  and  in  general, 
in  any  continuum,  indivisibles  ;  for  if  we  suppose  that  there 
are  an  infinite  number  of  extended  parts  in  a  continuum, 
the  resultant  of  these  parts  will  also  be  infinite.  Hence,  a 
line  must  be  composed  of  an  infinity  of  points  (the  Dichotomy 
and  Achilles),  time  of  an  infinity  of  instants  (the  Arrow). 
Now,  we  have  proved  that  the  continuum  is  not  composed  of 
indivisibles  ;  and  not  only  this,  but  that  though  it  is  infinitely 
divisible,  it  is  not  actually  divided  at  all,  and  finally  that  the 
indivisibles  are  not  actual,  but  only  potential  in  it.  If  this 
be  conceded,  Zeno's  arguments  at  once  break  down,  for  there 
will  not  be  an  infinity  of  indivisibles  actually  in  the  con- 
tinuum ;  such  indivisibles  as  there  are  being  only  potentially 
present,  and  consequently  there  will  be  no  point  which  is 
actually  the  halfway  point  of  a  distance  which  is  being 
traversed,  no  actual  point  in  the  motion  of  Achilles  where  the 
tortoise  was  before,  no  moment  in  the  flight  of  the  arrow 
actually.  Thus  the  mover  does  not  divide  its  trajectory  into 
an  infinite  number  of  actual  parts,  whether  proportional  or 
aliquot  ;  but  into  two  indeterminate  parts,  that  already 
traversed,  and  that  .about  to  be  traversed  ;  which  are  both 
continually  changing.  If,  however,  we  admit  actual  indivis- 
ibles, and  actual  parts  in  the  continuum,  it  seems  that  the 
arguments  are  insoluble,  even  if  it  be  contended  that  the 
number  of  such  parts  is  finite  ;  for  the  parts  must  be  either 
extended  or  unextended  :    if  they  are  extended,  they  are 


THE  CONTINUUM  y7 

divisible,  and  if  they  are  unextended,  in  traversing  them  a 
body  will  not  move.  So  we  shall  have  either  an  infinite  pro- 
cess, or  the  absence  of  motion.  On  S.  Thomas's  theory,  on 
the  contrary,  a  moving  body  never  arrives  at  the  halfway 
point,  but  passes  through  a  potential  point,  the  hero  never 
arrives  at  the  points  in  the  path  of  the  tortoise,  but  passes 
through  infinity  of  potential  points,  the  arrow  is  never  at 
any  one  point  of  its  flight. 

Though  it  would  be  true  to  say  that  an  infinite  distance 
could  not  be  traversed  in  a  finite  time,  yet  it  is  not  true  that  a 
distance  which  is  only  potentially  infinite  cannot  be  traversed 
in  a  finite  time  ;  for  both  space  and  time  are  infinitely 
divisible,  but  not  infinitely  divided  ;  so  that  it  is  possible  to 
pass  over  an  infinitely  divisible  space  in  a  finite  time,  since 
this  time  is  itself  infinitely  divisible. 


CHAPTER  VI 

PLACE   AND   SPACE 

I.  Place — Localisation — Kinds  of  Location.  II.  Space — Its  Nature 
— Opinions — Absolutist,  Subjectivist,  Intermediate  Theories — 
The  Void — Conclusion  as  to  the  Nature  of  Space.  III. 
The  Occupation  of  Space — Impenetrability — Multilocation. 

At  the  beginning  of  our  discussion  of  the  continuum,  we 
noticed  that  it  is  of  two  kinds,  permanent  and  successive. 
We  must  now  examine  these  separately.  Now  the  permanent 
continuum  is  concerned  with  the  extension  of  bodies,  and 
bodies,  in  so  far  as  they  are  extended,  are  said  to  be  in  space  ; 
and  as  occupying  a  defined  portion  of  it,  are  said  to  be  in 
place.    It  is  necessary  therefore  to  analyse  these  two  notions. 

Section  I.    On  Place. 

Though  the  notion  of  place  is,  in  a  certain  sense,  included 
in  that  of  space,  and  dependent  on  it,  yet  being  one  which  is 
clearer  and  more  familiar  to  us  than  that  of  space,  it  will  be 
more  convenient  to  consider  it  first. 

Place  is  defined  by  Aristotle  as  :  T6  tov  wepuxovros  ^v0? 
dxivrjTov  TrpQrov,  i.e.  the  first  unmoved  limit  of  the  container.1 
The  word  '  unmoved  '  indicates  that  the  surface,  which 
is  said  to  be  unmoved,  is  so  formally  as  a  limit ;  not 
that  the  interior  surface  of  the  container,  viz.  this  or 
that  vessel  which  contains  the  thing  which  is  in  place,  is 
unmoved.  Thus,  in  the  case  of  a  ship  anchored  at  sea,  though 
the  water  is  constantly  moving  round  it,  yet  the  containing 
limit  of  the  water,  as  such,  may  remain  unmoved.  How  are 
we  to  tell  whether  it  is  or  not  ?  Evidently,  we  must  gauge  it 
either  with  reference  to  something  which  is  absolutely  immov- 
able, or  which  at  least  is  unmoved  for  all  practical  purposes. 
Now,  we  do  not  know  of  any  body  in  the  material  universe  of 

1  Phys.,  212*  20. 
78 


PLACE  AND  SPACE  79 

which  we  can  say  that  it  is  absolutely  immovable,  but  for 
practical  purposes  the  poles  and  the  centre  of  the  earth  are 
unmoved,  and  consequently  we  calculate  the  place  of  a  body 
with  reference  to  them.  So,  S.  Thomas  says  :  '  Although 
this  container  may  move,  in  so  far  as  it  is  this  body,  never- 
theless as  it  is  considered  with  respect  to  the  relation  which 
it  has  to  the  whole  body  of  the  heaven,  it  is  not  moved,  for 
any  body  which  succeeds  it,  has  the  same  order  or  position 
with  respect  to  the  whole  heaven,  which  the  body,  which 
earlier  passed  away,  had.'1 

Modern  Scholastics  often  distinguish  between  external  and 
internal  place.  The  former  is  that  of  which  we  have  just 
been  speaking,  while  by  the  latter  they  mean  the  capacity 
which  is  circumscribed  by  the  exterior  surface  of  the  body, 
i.e.  it  is  the  portion  of  space  which  the  body  occupies,  and 
which  exactly  corresponds  with  its  real  volume.  It  seems 
doubtful,  however,  whether  this  distinction  can  be  main- 
tained, as  it  appears  that  such  internal  place  would  not  be 
real.2  When  the  word  place  is  used,  then,  it  is  to  external 
place  that  reference  is  made. 

Aristotle  distinguishes  between  the  proper  and  common 
place  of  a  body  :  proper  place  being  that  which  immediately 
surrounds  the  thing  which  is  in  place,  so  that  it  is  in  con- 
tact with  it  alone  ;  while  common  place  is  that  which  does 
not  immediately  surround  the  thing,  but  surrounds  it  in 
common  with  other  things  ;  as  in  a  nest  of  Chinese  boxes, 
each  one  containing  a  smaller  one,  the  proper  place  of  each 
might  be  said  to  be  the  box  next  greater  than  itself,  while 
the  common  place  of  all,  but  the  outermost  but  one,  would 
be  the  outside  box  of  all. 

The  accident  resulting  in  a  located  thing  from  the  fact 
that  it  is  subject  to  external  place  is  called  '  ubi  '  or  localisa- 
tion. As  to  the  nature  of  this  accident  opinions  differ,  for 
some  think  it  is  a  mere  mental  relation,  and  not  real  at  all  ; 
for  they  think  the  body  must  be  the  same  in  itself  whether  it 
is  in  one  place  or  another,  so  that  by  local  motion  it  acquires 

1  IV  Phys.,  Lect.  6.  No.  9. 

2  But  cf.  Nys,  La  Notion  de  I'Espace  (pp.  236-278),  who  argues  at  length 
in  favour  of  this  distinction,  and  the  reality  of  internal  place. 


8o  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

nothing  but  a  change  of  position  relatively  to  other  objects. 
This,  indeed,  seems  to  us  nowadays  the  obvious  view  to  take, 
and  accords  well  with  the  Cartesian  theory  of  motion  men- 
tioned above  ;  and  is  probably,  as  Whitehead  suggests,  '  the 
very  foundation  of  the  seventeeth  century  scheme  of  nature.'1 
Nevertheless,  local  motion  seems  to  imply  more  than  a  mere 
change  of  position  ;  for,  supposing,  while  a  body  was  in 
motion,  all  others  were  to  be  annihilated  ;  according  to  this 
theory,  since  it  could  not  change  its  position  relatively  to 
them,  its  motion  would  cease  :  a  conclusion  which  can  hardly 
be  accepted  since  the  motion  was  not  caused  by  the  presence 
of  other  bodies,  and  could  not  therefore  be  destroyed  by 
their  removal.  Further,  the  relation  which  the  located  body 
has  to  its  environment  is  certainly  a  real  one  independent  of 
our  thought  of  it,  and  consequently  requires  a  real  founda- 
tion.2 Now,  this  foundation  cannot  be  the  quantity  of  the 
body,  as  is  suggested,  for,  though  it  is  true  that  the  body  is 
located  by  means  of  its  quantity,  yet  it  can  have  different 
locations  while  retaining  the  same  quantity.  There  must, 
therefore,  be,  in  the  body,  some  additional  reality  over  and 
above  quantity,  which  is  the  foundation  of  this  or  that 
localisation,  i.e.  application  of  the  body  to  this  or  that  place. 
For,  in  so  far  as  contact  is  made  with  a  second  place,  a  new 
relationship  is  acquired  by  the  body.  The  fact  that  the 
foundation  of  this  relation  is  in  the  located  body,  even 
though  the  relation  is  derived  from  without,  owing  to  the 
presence  of  the  surrounding  bodies,  is  in  no  sense  a  contradic- 
tion ;  for  the  foundation  and  the  relation  arise  simultaneously ; 
the  foundation  being  the  formal  cause  of  the  relation,  i.e.  that 
by  which  the  relation  is  constituted,  the  extrinsic  circum- 
scription by  the  other  bodies  being  the  efficient  cause  of  this 

1  Whitehead,  Science  and  the  Modern  World,  p.  72. 

2  As  will  be  explained  more  fully  later,  the  Scholastics  recognise  three 
elements  in  a  relation  :  the  subject,  the  term,  and  the  foundation  ;  all  of 
which,  in  the  case  of  a  real  relation,  must  be  real.  The  subject  is  that 
thing  in  which  the  relation  is  present,  the  term  that  towards  which  it  is 
directed,  and  the  foundation  that  by  which  the  relation  is  constituted, 
i.e.  the  reason  why  the  subject  is  related  to  the  term.  So  in  the  relation 
of  sonship,  the  subject  is  the  boy  who  is  generated,  the  term  is  the  parent, 
and  the  foundation  the  fact  of  being  generated.  Here,  then,  the  foundation 
is  caused  by  the  act  of  generation  of  the  parents,  while  it  constitutes  the 
son  as  standing  in  a  certain  relation  to  them. 


PLACE   AND   SPACE  81 

foundation.  It  would,  however,  be  absurd  to  rush  to  the 
other  extreme,  and  say  that  this  accident  was  something 
absolute,  intrinsic  to  the  located  body,  for  it  clearly  arises  as 
a  result  of  its  quantity  being  commensurate  with  those  of  its 
particular  surroundings,  and  hence  is  something  which  comes 
to  it  from  without,  and  so  is  not  '  secundum  substantiam,  vel 
secundum  aliquam  intrinsecam  dispositionem  substantia  n — 
such  as  quantity  or  quality — as  S.  Thomas  says  repeatedly. 
It  seems,  therefore,  that  it  is  a  real  mode  which  comes  to  the 
body  from  without.  This  theory  does  not,  as  the  one  men- 
tioned above  seems  to  do,  render  the  admission  of  motion  in 
a  completely  empty  space  impossible,  for  change  of  localisa- 
tion is  not  here  identified  with  motion,  but  is  considered  to  be 
an  effect  of  it,  so  that  even  if  there  were  no  localisation,  and 
consequently  no  change  of  it,  motion  could  still  continue.2 

It  is  worth  noticing  that  the  reality  of  local  motion  is  safe- 
guarded by  both  these  theories,  since  in  the  first  there  is  a 
succession  of  real  contacts,  and  in  the  second  a  connected 
succession  of  real  modes  by  whose  means  the  different  real 
contacts  are  effected. 

The  Scholastics  point  out  that  there  are  several  ways  in 
which  a  thing  may  be  in  place. 

First,  there  is  the  way  of  which  we  have  just  been  speaking, 
viz.  circumscriptive  location, which  is  predicamental  location. 
This  is  the  passive  circumscription  of  a  body  which  arises 
from  its  actually  being  surrounded  by  a  place. 

But  a  thing  may  also  be  in  place  '  not  circumscriptively,' 
and  this  either  naturally  or  praeternaturally.  Naturally 
either  by  operation,  i.e.  by  acting  on  a  place,  as  an  angel 
may  do  ;3  or  by  informing  a  body,  which  is  circumscriptively 
in  place,  as  the  human  soul  does.  The  theologians  enumerate 
three  preternatural  modes  of  being  in  place,  viz.  eucharistic- 
ally,  infernally,  and  hypostatically. 

A  thing  is  said  to  be  definitely  in  place,  if  it  is  so  limited  to 
one  place  as  not  to  be  able  to  be  at  the  same  time  in  another. 
Evidently  it  is  only  bodies  which  are  in  place  circumscrip- 
tively, and,  as  we  shall  see  shortly,  they  must  also  be  in 

1  XII  Met.  S.  Thomas,  Lect.  7  (ed.  Cathala,  2530). 

2  Cf.  Nys,  op.  cit.,  pp.  254,  264  f. 

8  Summa  Theol.,  Pars  I,  Q.  52,  a.  I. 


-82  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

place  definitively,  i.e.  they  cannot  be  in  two  places  at 
once. 

Owing  to  the  importance  of  the  subject,  we  may  perhaps 
be  allowed  to  notice  that  the  body  of  Christ  in  the  Eucharist 
is  in  place  neither  circumscriptively  nor  definitively,  as  is 
plain  from  the  definitions  given.  It  is  only  metaphorically 
that  we  say  that  It  is  in  place  ;  indeed  it  is  only  those  things 
which  are  in  place  circumscriptively,  which  are  in  place 
properly  speaking,  so  that  an  angel,  or  the  human  soul  are 
only  in  place  metaphorically,  in  somewhat  the  same  way  as 
when  we  speak  of  a  discussion  or  remark  being  '  in  or  out  of 
place,'1 

From  what  has  been  said,  it  will  be  seen  that  there  is  a 
very  close  connection  between  the  notions  of  place  and  space  ; 
and  we  are  thus  naturally  led  to  consider  the  latter. 

Section  II.     On  Space. 

Although  the  greatest  divergence  of  opinion  is  to  be  found 
among  philosophers  as  to  the  nature  of  space,  yet  these 
opinions  are  linked  together  by  the  degree  of  reality  which 
they  attribute  to  it ;  and  may  be  classified  under  three  heads  : 
the  theories  (i)  of  those  who  emphasise  this  reality,  (2)  of 
those  who  emphasise  its  ideal  character,  and  (3)  of  those  who 
preserve  the  balance  between  the  two.  The  last  group  of 
opinions  will  have  a  prima  facie  claim  to  be  preferred  as 
being  a  mean  which  preserves  the  truths  pointed  out  by  both 
the  other  groups. 

The  difficulty  of  the  question  consists  in  this,  that  if  we 
make  something  real  of  space  in  itself,  we  shall  be  logically 
led  to  say  that  space  without  bodies  is  something  real,  or 
that  absolute  space  is  something  real,  which  is  a  purely 
gratuitous  assertion,  based  on  no  evidence  ;  and  one,  more- 
over, which  would  make  space  itself  unintelligible  ;  since,  if 
all  bodies  are  removed,  leaving  real  space  behind,  this  space 
must  be  immaterial.  It  is,  however,  the  function  of  space  to 
be  the  location  of  bodies,  and  apart  from  this  function  we 
seem  to  have  no  conception  of  it.  It  is,  moreover,  clear  that 
the  material  cannot  be  located  in  the  immaterial,  and  so  by 

1  Cf.  Salmanticenses,  De  Angelis,  Vol.  IV,  pp.  83  S. 


PLACE  AND  SPACE  83 

making  space  real  we  deprive  it  of  its  only  meaning,  and 
render  it  unintelligible.  On  the  other  hand,  if  we  say  that 
space  is  not  real,  we  shall  seem  to  contradict  common  sense, 
to  speak  in  a  way  which  is  in  disagreement  with  scientific 
language,  and  to  deprive  the  material  world  of  its  objectivity. 

Can  these  and  similar  objections  on  one  side,  or  the  other, 
be  met,  or  must  we  try  to  reconcile  the  two  views  ?  Such  is 
the  question  to  be  answered. 

I.  Turning,  then,  to  the  first  group  of  opinions,  of  those, 
namely,  who  insist  on  the  reality  of  space  ;  we  find  among 
the  Greek  philosophers  some  who  regarded  space  as  absolute. 

1.  Thus  Democritus,  and  others  who  took  a  similar  view 
of  nature,  taught  that  space  is  the  vacuum,  or  a  universal 
receptacle,  which  is  distinct  from  bodies,  but  in  which  they 
move.  Similarly,  some  Peripatetics  taught  that  space  is  a 
kind  of  immense  sphere  which  surrounds  all  bodies.  Gassendi, 
in  the  seventeenth  century,  reviving  the  old  Atomism, 
adopted  this  view  of  space,  but  tried  to  rid  it  of  some  of  its 
absurdities,  by  denying  to  it  the  character  of  absolute 
necessity,  which  had  been  given  it,  and  saying  that  it  has  a 
reality  which  does  not  come  within  our  categories,  being 
neither  substance  nor  accident.  Locke  (1632-1704)  also 
seems  to  incline  to  the  ultra-realist  opinion,  which  would 
substantialise  space,  though  his  way  of  speaking  is  by  no 
means  free  of  ambiguity.1  He,  like  Gassendi,  suggests  that 
space  may  be  thought  of  as  a  substance,  granting  that '  sub- 
stance '  be  taken  in  a  different  sense  from  that  in  which  we 
ordinarily  use  it.  The  word,  he  says,  has  already  three 
different  senses  as  applied  to  God,  spirits,  and  bodies  :  why 
not  add  a  fourth  to  apply  to  space  ? 

If  we  examine  these  notions  one  by  one  we  shall  see  that 
all  of  them  involve  inconsistencies.  So  the  suggestion  that 
space,  the  receptacle  of  bodies,  is  the  vacuum,  is  untenable, 
since  the  bodies  are  extended,  and  so  their  receptacle  must 
be  extended  also.  The  vacuum,  however,  of  the  Atomists 
was  unextended,  and  so  cannot  be  space.  Even  if  it  were 
thought  of  as  extended,  it  would  need  a  further  receptacle 

1  Cf.  Essay  on  the  Human  Understanding,  Bk.  II,  Ch.  XIII,  Nos.  5  ff., 
especially  No.  22  ;   and  Nys,  op.  cit.,  pp.  37  ff. 


84  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

or  vacuum  to  contain  it,  and  so  we  should  have  an  unending 
series  of  vacua  containing  one  another,  without  ever  arriving 
at  an  ultimate  space.  This  last  objection  militates  equally 
against  Gassendi's  view,  for  whom  the  receptacle  of  bodies 
was  extended,  and  the  very  reason  which,  in  his  opinion, 
makes  it  necessary  to  imagine  a  first  receptacle,  viz.  that  an 
extended  thing  must  be  received  in  something,  would  apply 
with  equal  force  to  this  receptacle  itself,  and  so  on  to  infinity. 
Further,  this  space  was  thought  of  as  eternal  independent 
being.  Such  being,  however,  would  be  unproduced,  and  pure 
act,  which  is  in  direct  contradiction  with  the  notion  of  space 
as  the  receptacle  of  bodies,  which  must  necessarily  imply  a 
universal  potentiality  for  receiving  them. 

2.  Such  views  as  these  seem  to  deify  space,  and  this  idea 
that  space  is  an  attribute' of  the  Deity,  is  found  explicitly  in 
the  opinion  of  Newton  and  Clarke,  though  the  latter,  under 
the  pressure  of  the  objections  of  Leibniz,  modified  his  original 
position  to  some  extent.  Thus  Newton  identifies  it  with 
God's  omnipresence,  and  Clarke  with  His  immensity.  So,  in  a 
curious  passage,  Newton  writes  :  '  Is  not  the  sensory  of 
animals  that  place  to  which  the  sensitive  substance  is  present, 
and  into  which  the  sensible  species  of  things  are  carried 
through  the  nerves  and  the  brain,  that  there  they  may  be 
perceived  by  their  immediate  presence  to  that  substance  ? 
And  these  things  being  rightly  dispatched,  does  it  not  appear 
from  phenomena  that  there  is  a  Being  incorporeal,  living, 
intelligent,  omnipresent,  who,  in  infinite  space,  as  it  were 
in  his  sensory,  sees  the  things  themselves  intimately,  and 
thoroughly  perceives  them,  and  comprehends  them  wholly 
by  their  immediate  presence  to  himself  ;  of  which  things  the 
images  only  (i.e.  on  the  retina)  carried  through  the  organs  of 
sense  into  our  little  sensoriums,  are  then  seen  and  beheld  by 
that  which  in  us  perceives  and  thinks.'1  Now,  if  there  is  one 
thing  which  is  clear  about  the  divine  attributes,  such  as 
omnipresence  and  immensity,  it  is  that  they  must  be  iden- 
tical with  the  divine  nature,  and  so  an  absolute  unity.  This 
is  in  evident  conflict  with  that  most  fundamental  character- 

1  Opticks,  pp.  344  ff.  (quoted  by  Burtt,  Metaphysical  Foundations  of 
Modern  Science,  p.  258). 


PLACE  AND  SPACE  85 

istic  of  space  which  is  its  extension  and  divisibility.  More- 
over, such  a  theory  would  lead  straight  to  Pantheism,  since 
space  is  an  attribute  of  bodies,  and  so  can  only  be  held  to  be 
also  an  attribute  of  God  by  Pantheists. 

This  is,  in  fact,  the  view  adopted  in  the  pantheistic  philo- 
sophy of  Spinoza,  Starting  with  the  Cartesian  notion  that 
the  nature  of  bodies  consists  of  their  triple  extension,  he 
follows  him  also  in  asserting  that  there  is  only  a  logical  dis- 
tinction between  space  and  extension.  There  are,  he  con- 
siders, two  aspects  in  which  space  is  viewed  by  us.  In  the 
first  place,  we  imagine  it  as  composed  of  parts,  and  so  divis- 
ible, and,  in  fact,  divided  :  its  parts  being  what  we  call 
bodies.  Secondly,  the  intellectual  consideration  of  space 
shows  us  that  it  is,  in  fact,  a  common  reality,  viz.  substantial 
extension  in  three  dimensions,  which  is  everywhere  the  same, 
absolutely  indivisible,  and  positively  infinite.  Such  an 
entity  can  be  nothing  else  than  an  attribute  of  God.1  Now, 
we  cannot  concede  the  second  part  of  this  theory,  since  it  is 
clear  that  extension  implies  a  non-coincidence  of  parts,  and 
is  therefore  essentially  divisible. 

A  theory  having  marked  affinities  with  those  of  Newton 
and  Spinoza  has  recently  been  evolved  by  Professor  S. 
Alexander  in  his  work,  Space,  Time  and  Deity,  according  to 
whom  the  whole  universe,  whose  reality  is  Space-Time, 
which  is  progressively  evolving,  is  to  be  identified  with  God.2 
This  idea  is  open  to  the  objections  raised  against  Spinoza, 
and,  in  addition,  God  is  represented  as  progressing  or  evolv- 
ing, and,  in  fact,  never  coming  to  be.  Such  a  '  Being  '  is 
evidently  imperfect  and  finite,  so  that  the  name  God  is 
applied  to  it  equivocally,  i.e.  in  a  wholly  different  sense  to 
that  intended  by  Theists  when  using  the  word.  Alexander's 
God  is  not  their  God. 

II.  The  Second  Group.    The  Ultra-Sub jectivist  theories. 

1.  If  the  Absolutist  views  of  space  thus  fail  to  satisfy  us, 
perhaps  we  may  find  a  more  adequate  idea  of  it  among  the 
Subjectivist  theories.  The  first  of  them  to  claim  our  atten- 
tion is  that  of  Kant.    According  to  him,  we  cannot  know 

1  Spinoza,  Ethica,  Pars  I,  Prop.  15,  Scholium. 

2  Vol.  II,  pp.  428  fif. 


86  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

whether  the  external  world  has  those  characteristics  which 
we  attribute  to  it,  and  so  whether  '  things-in-themselves ' 
are  extended,  distant  from  one  another,  and  so  on  :  all  we 
can  say  is  that  they  appear  to  be  so  to  us.  Now  this  spatial 
appearance  might  derive  either  from  the  things,  or  from  us. 
Just  as  to  a  man  crossing  to  France  in  a  Channel  steamer  the 
sea  might  appear  yellow ;  and  this  appearance  might  be 
caused  either  by  the  flood  waters  of  some  river  running  into 
it  and  discolouring  it,  or  to  the  disturbed  state  of  the  man's 
liver  ;  so,  in  the  case  of  space,  the  spatial  appearance  might 
be  due  either  to  things  sensed  being  spatial,  or  to  the  consti- 
tution of  our  senses  ;  and  Kant  argues  that  we  see  that  this 
latter  supposition  is  the  true  one  from  the  fact  that  space  is  a 
general  form,  which  applies  universally  to  the  whole  material 
world.  Now,  the  thing-in-itself  is  singular,  and  so  cannot 
contain,  or  transmit  to  us  the  universal.  Hence  this  form 
must  be  part  of  the  constitution  of  our  minds  or  senses. 
What,  then,  is  space  ?  It  is  a  part  of  the  pattern  of  our 
senses,  and  so  Kant  calls  it  an  '  a  priori  form  of  the  sensi- 
bility.' It  is  a  priori,  in  a  way  somewhat  similar  to  that  in 
which  the  shape  of  a  '  castle  pudding '  may  be  said  to  be 
given  a  priori :  it  is  that  particular  shape  because  of  the 
mould  in  which  it  is  made.  So  the  senses,  having  a  particular 
mould  (of  space  and  time),  turn  out  the  objects  marked  with 
this  mould  or  pattern.  It  is  seen  to  be  a  priori,  since  it 
logically  precedes  any  sensible  experience  ;  in  saying  which, 
Kant  wishes  it  to  be  clear  that  he  does  not  think  that  it 
really  precedes  it,  as  if  we  could  know  space  before  we  know 
sense-objects  :  but  it  is  present  in  the  sensibility  in  a  similar 
way  to  that  in  which  an  image  on  a  photographic  film  may 
be  said  to  be  present  in  it  before  the  film  is  developed  :  as 
soon  as  the  acids  are  applied  to  it  the  image  will  come  up. 
Similarly,  as  soon  as  the  sense-objects  are  applied  to  the 
sensibility,  the  forms  of  space  and  time  will,  as  it  were, 
develop  up.  Further,  he  calls  it '  pure,'  since  it  is  not  derived 
from  any  experience  ;  and  finally,  it  is  necessary,  as  being 
an  essential  condition  of  all  sensible  experience. 

The  most  fundamental  criticism  of  this  view  is  that  which 
shows   the   inconsistency   in    Kant's    distinction   between 


PLACE  AND  SPACE  87 

appearance  and  reality,  between  phenomena  and  things-in- 
themselves  ;  for,  according  to  Kant,  not  only  is  space 
phenomenal  and  a  priori,  but  the  same  is  true  of  the  notions 
of  cause  and  existence,  which  he  calls  a  priori  categories  of 
the  mind.  The  reality,  therefore,  can  be  neither  a  cause  nor 
existing.  If  this  be  so,  we  are  faced  with  a  contradiction,  for 
our  sensations,  though  not  their  forms,  are  in  Kant's  view 
caused  by  the  thing  in  itself ;  which  must  therefore  exist. 
But,  according  to  him,  as  we  said,  it  can  neither  exist  nor 
cause,  if  existence  and  causality  apply  only  to  phenomena. 
Further,  on  Kant's  theory,  it  is  impossible  to  give  any 
coherent  account  of  the  change  and  movement  which  we 
perceive  among  bodies.  For  this  movement,  even  if  it  is 
only  phenomenal,  is  at  least  a  real  phenomenon  which  must 
therefore  have  some  cause.  This  could  only  be  the  a  priori 
form  of  space,  or  some  influence  external  to  the  senses.  Now, 
Kant's  theory  will  not  admit  of  either  of  these  explanations 
of  its  source  ;  for,  in  the  first  place,  the  a  priori  form  is 
logically  prior  to  all  phenomena,  and  essentially  static,  since 
it  is  a  form  of  our  nature,  from  which  it  receives  its  function 
of  making  the  phenomena  appear  as  extended  in  three 
dimensions,  and  only  three.  Hence,  though  it  may  imply 
relative  position,  it  cannot  give  us  change  of  position, 
direction,  distance,  etc.,  which  are  things  quite  extraneous 
to  the  form  of  space  as  such  ;  which  would  equally  well  be 
preserved  in  an  entirely  static  world,  implying,  as  it  does, 
nothing  more  than  three-dimensional  extension.  In  the 
second  place,  it  is  even  more  impossible  that  the  appearance 
of  spatial  change  should  be  derived  from  external  influences, 
for,  in  this  case,  the  a  priori  character  of  the  space-form 
would  be  destroyed.1 

2.  A  second  view  of  the  ultra-sub jectivist  type  is  that  of 
Leibniz,  who  thought  of  space  as  '  something  purely  relative 
...  as  an  order  of  coexistences.  Space  denotes,  in  terms  of 
possibility,  the  order  of  those  things  which  exist  at  the  same 
time,  in  so  far  as  they  exist  together  ;   leaving  on  one  side 

1  Cf.  Nys,  op.  cit.,  p.  79.  For  a  detailed  criticism  of  Kant's  theory  see 
Pritchard.  Kant's  Theory  of  Knowledge,  Chaps.  Ill  and  IV,  and  Nys, 
Ch.  II. 


88  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

their  way  of  existing.  Whenever  we  see  several  things 
together,  we  are  conscious  of  such  an  order  of  the  things 
among  themselves.'1 

Consistently,  therefore,  with  his  cosmological  theory, 
according  to  which  the  world  is  composed  of  unextended 
monads,  he  banishes  space  altogether  from  reality,  and  makes 
of  it  something  purely  mental  or  ideal.2 

We  already  noticed  one  radical  defect  of  this  theory,  when 
we  showed  that  it  is  impossible  for  the  notion,  or  appearance, 
of  extension— and  so  of  space — to  arise  in  our  minds  unless 
there  be  some  spatial  extension  somewhere  in  reality  :  but 
we  may  mention  here  some  difficulties  which  belong  peculiarly 
to  this  view  of  space.  For,  in  the  first  place,  the  coexistence 
of  things,  and  a  fortiori  the  order  of  coexistences,  presupposes 
space,  since  they  are  said  to  coexist  precisely  because  they 
appear  to  exist  together  in  different  parts  of  space.  Con- 
sequently, since  the  order  of  coexistences  presupposes  space, 
it  cannot  constitute  it.  In  the  second  place,  the  attributes 
of  space  must  apply  to  the  order  of  coexistences  if  these  two 
are  identical.  Now,  space  is  said  to  be  full,  empty,  and  equal 
to  the  located  thing,  none  of  which  predicates  can  be  applied 
to  the  order  of  coexistences,  since  an  order,  or  relation, 
cannot  be  full,  empty  or  equal.  In  the  third  place,  things 
which  coexist  must  be  bound  together  by  some  common  link, 
which  cannot  be  true  of  the  Leibnizian  coexistents,  seeing 
that  they  are  simple  monads  without  extension.  In  Leib- 
niz's view  the  monads  do  not  interact  in  any  way,  but  are 
like  the  puppets  in  a  marionette  show,  which  appear  to  bow 
and  speak  to  one  another,  but  are,  in  fact,  controlled  entirely 
by  the  showman  :  they  are  not  related  to  one  another,  but 
to  the  man  behind  the  scenes.  In  a  similar  way,  the  monads 
have  no  connection  with  one  another,  but  only  with  God, 
who  destined  them  by  pre-established  harmony  to  act  in  a 
certain  way.  So  there  is  no  common  link  between  them,  and 
they  cannot  be  said,  in  any  direct  sense,  to  coexist.  Leibniz, 
in  fact,  recognised  the  gravity  of  this  difficulty,  and  tried  to 
meet  it — and  other  cognate  ones — by  his  elusive  doctrine  of 

1  Correspondence  with  Clarke,  third  letter  of  Leibniz,  No.  4. 
*  Cf.  Nys,  op.  cit.,  pp.  121  f.    Wildon  Carr,  Leibniz,  pp.  156  ff. 


PLACE  AND  SPACE  89 

the  '  vinculum  substantiate,'  a.  real  substantial  link,  and  a 
reality  other  than  the  monads,  from  which  alone  continuity 
is  said  to  arise.  This  seems  rather  to  add  to  the  difficulty, 
than  diminish  it,  since  it  is  not  easy  to  see  how  it  can  be 
reconciled  with  the  independence  of  the  monads,  which  is  a 
central  doctrine  of  Leibnizianism.  The  notion  of  the 
vinculum  substantiate  was  introduced  in  an  attempt  to 
reconcile  his  theory  with  the  Scholastic  idea  that  bodies, 
e.g.  of  animals,  are  unities  per  se,  not  mere  aggregates.1 

Lastly,  space  would  still  be  preserved  if  there  were  only 
one  body  in  the  world  ;  but,  evidently,  in  this  case,  there 
would  be  no  order  of  coexistences,  and  consequently  these 
cannot  be  identified. 

III.  The  Intermediate  Theories.  We  now  turn  to  the 
intermediate  theories,  which  make  space  neither  a  reality  on 
its  own  account,  nor  yet  wholly  ideal. 

1.  The  first  of  these  is  the  view  of  Descartes,  Balmes,  and 
Palmieri,  which  identifies  space  with  extension.  They  say 
that  when  we  think  of  space,  we  abstract  from  the  extension 
of  bodies,  and  give  to  space  a  generic  unity,  without  division, 
so  that  we  can  speak  of  bodies  moving  in  space.  Conse- 
quently, our  notion  of  space  has  no  counterpart  in  nature, 
but  is  nevertheless  based  on  something  found  in  nature,  viz. 
the  extension  of  bodies. 

Hence,  space  is,  according  to  these  philosophers,  abstract 
extension.  We  have  called  this  an  intermediate  view,  and 
indeed  it  does  seem  to  try  and  mediate  between  the  extreme 
realists  and  the  extreme  idealists.  Unfortunately,  however, 
like  so  many  peacemakers,  it  only  succeeds  in  receiving  the 
blows  which  the  rivals  aim  at  one  another.  For,  if  space  be 
identical  with  corporeal  extension,  it  will  certainly  be  real, 
and  in  Descartes'  system,  an  absolute  reality  ;  since  there 
can  never  be  a  vacuum  ;  and  so  matter  must  be  indefinitely 
extended.  Space,  then,  from  this  point  of  view,  will  be  an 
absolute,  infinite,  real  being,  and  open  to  all  the  attacks 
which  the  idealists  make  on  the  ultra-real  views  of  space, 
such  as  those  of  Clarke  and  Spinoza.     On  the  other  hand, 

1  Cf.  Epistola  ad  Pattern  des  Bosses,  29  May,  1716;  and  Latta, 
Monadology,  etc.,  pp.  118  ff.    (Oxford  Univ.  Press.) 


90  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

since  this  theory  denies  that  our  conception  of  space  corres- 
ponds to  anything  found  in  nature,  it  seems  to  make  of  space 
something  purely  mental,  and  so  falls  a  victim  to  the  blows 
which  the  realists  aim  at  the  idealists,  such  as  Leibniz  or 
Kant.  Apart  from  the  awkward  position  in  which  it  finds 
itself,  as  combining  the  disadvantages  of  both  the  other 
theories,  the  notion  that  space  is  to  be  identified  with  exten- 
sion will  not  bear  investigation,  for  though  it  is  true  that 
there  are  many  characteristics,  such  as  stretching  out,  being 
measurable,  divisible,  and  so  on,  which  belong  both  to  space 
and  extension,  yet  space  has  at  least  one  characteristic  which 
is  contrary  to  that  of  extension  ;  for  we  conceive  of  space  as 
that  which  is  filled  and  occupied  by  bodies,  while  extension 
is  that  by  means  of  which  a  body  fills  or  occupies  space. 
Consequently,  far  from  being  formally  identified,  space  and 
extension  are  formally  opposed,  as  the  filled  and  the  filler, 
the  occupied  and  the  occupier.  The  truth,  therefore,  is  that 
these  two  are  not  identical,  but  that  the  notion  of  space 
includes  that  of  extension. 

2.  The  second  of  these  intermediate  opinions  is  that  of 
Suarez  and  many  other  Scholastics,  as  de  Backer,  Dario,  and 
others,  according  to  whom  space  is  a  logical  being  with  a  real 
foundation.  They  conceive  it,  in  itself,  as  an  empty  recep- 
tacle which  is  capable  of  containing  bodies,  real  space  being 
that  portion  of  absolute  space  which  is  occupied  by  real 
bodies.  This  opinion,  like  the  last,  is  attacked  from  two 
sides ;  since  Nys,1  as  it  seems  justly,  accuses  it  of  taking 
away  all  reality  from  space,  while  others  say  that  it  gives  it 
too  much.  For,  according  to  Suarez,  absolute  space  is  not 
real,  and  what  is  called  real  space  in  this  theory  is  merely  a 
portion  of  this  absolute  or  imaginary  space  ;  and  so  will  be 
as  ideal  as  it  is,  since  the  portions  of  such  ideal  space  cannot 
become  real  from  the  mere  fact  that  real  bodies  are  present 
in  them,  nor  from  any  of  their  properties,  since  in  this  view 
the  parts  of  space  are  carefully  distinguished  from  any  of  the 
realities  of  the  bodies  which  occupy  them.  Space,  then,  on 
this  view,  appears  to  remain  a  purely  ideal  entity,  a  con- 
ception which  seems  irreconcilable  with  the  notion  of  space 
1  Cf.  Nys,  op.  cit.,  pp.  177  ff. 


PLACE  AND  SPACE  91 

as  the  receptacle  of  bodies,  and  the  field  of  their  real 
motion. 

On  the  other  hand,  Hoenen  maintains  that  the  theory  is 
ultra-realist,  as  making  a  reality  of  absolute  or  imaginary 
space,  since,  in  this  opinion,  it  is  held  that  a  single  body 
would  have  in  itself  a  determinate  localisation  in  space, 
irrespective  of  any  extrinsic  relations  to  others,  so  that  even 
if  there  were  only  one  body  in  the  world,  it  would  be  localised 
in  space  ;  and  so  could,  properly  speaking,  have  local  motion 
through  the  variation  of  this  intrinsic  location.1  There  is, 
in  fact,  an  inconsistency  in  this  theory,  for  either  absolute 
space  must  be  allowed  to  be  real,  in  which  case  Hoenen 's 
criticism  is  justified  ;  or  else,  as  is,  in  fact,  done  by  those 
who  hold  this  view,  its  reality  must  be  denied,  and  it  then 
becomes  impossible  to  say  that  a  single  body  will  of  itself  be 
really  present  in  any  part  of  it ;  and  space  will  be  something 
wholly  ideal.  Since,  then,  absolute  space  is  not  allowed  to 
be  real,  it  seems  that  the  criticism  of  Nys  is  justified. 

3.  We  now  pass  to  the  opinion  which  regards  space  as  the 
interval  between  bodies.  Even  here  we  have  a  divergence 
of  views,  for  some  hold  that  space  is  the  interval  between 
the  confines  of  a  single  body,  others  that  it  is  constituted  by 
the  relation  of  distance  which  holds  between  several  bodies, 
which  relation  rests  on  the  accidents  which  localise  these 
bodies.  The  latter  is  the  view  of  Nys,  and  can  be  explained 
as  follows  : 

(a)  Since  all  are  agreed  in  conceiving  space  as  the  recep- 
tacle of  real  bodies,  we  start  our  investigation  with  this 
conception.  Now,  it  seems  clear  that  such  a  receptacle  must 
be  a  three-dimensional  relation  of  distance  containing  them, 
i.e.  a  three-dimensional  relation  of  distance  which  connects 
the  related  terms  ;  and  so  is  such  a  relation  between  real 
bodies,  the  foundations  of  this  relation  being  the  localising 
accidents  which  give  to  the  bodies  a  certain  situation  in  the 
universe.  That  the  receptacle  must  be  three-dimensional  is 
clear,  since  it  must  be  able  to  contain  the  bodies,  which  are 
themselves  three-dimensional.  This  condition  is  not  only  the 
necessary  one  for  such  a  receptacle,  it  is  also  sufficient,  since 

1  Cf.  Hoenen,  Cosmologia,  pp.  109  f. 


92  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

to  contain  or  surround  a  body  requires  nothing  but  such 
extension,  the  composition  of  the  receptacle  in  other  ways 
being  irrelevant.1 

Apart,  however,  from  the  difficulty,  touched  on  when  we 
were  dealing  with  place,  of  allowing  that  the  accidents  which 
localise  a  body  are  something  which  it  has  of  itself  intrinsic- 
ally, and  which  are  not  derived  from  its  relation  to  others 
(and  of  such  a  kind  are  supposed  to  be  the  foundations  of  the 
relation  of  distance  in  this  theory)  there  is  another  difficulty 
in  it,  inasmuch  as  it  would  follow  from  it  that  a  single  body 
was  not  in  space,  which  seems  to  be  at  variance  with  the 
common  view  of  space,  and  our  ordinary  expressions  with 
regard  to  it,  as  when  we  say  :  '  This  street  '  or  '  this  room  is 
spacious.'  To  this  it  might  perhaps  be  replied  that  though 
we  may  imagine  a  single  body  to  be  in  space,  yet,  in  fact, 
considering  the  essential  elements  of  the  notion  of  space, 
viz.  that  it  is  a  receptacle,  and  a  distance  capable  of  being 
traversed,  neither  of  these  conditions  would  be  fulfilled  in 
the  case  of  a  single  body  :  for,  being  single,  it  could  not  be 
received  in  anything,  since  there  is  nothing  else,  and  a  thing 
cannot  be  received  in  itself  ;  nor  would  the  distance  included 
between  its  limits  be  capable  of  being  traversed,  for  it  would 
either  have  to  be  traversed  by  some  body  other  than  itself, 
which  is  impossible,  since,  by  hypothesis,  no  other  body 
exists,  or  else  by  some  part  of  itself,  in  which  case  the  body 
would  be  broken  up  and  would  no  longer  be  one  body. 
Neither  of  these  replies  is,  however,  really  satisfactory,  for 
even  though  a  single  body  could  not  be  actually  traversed 
owing  to  the  absence  of  anything  to  traverse  it,  yet  this 
evidently  arises  from  something  extrinsic,  and  not  essential 
to  the  body  itself,  which,  as  being  extended,  still  retains  its 
capacity  for  being  traversed.  So  it  would  be  as  absurd  to 
say  that  an  absolute  desert  was  incapable  of  being  traversed 
because  there  was  nothing  to  traverse  it ;  as  that  a  man 
living  alone  in  a  hermitage  had  lost  the  power  of  speech 
because  he  had  no  one  to  talk  to.  Further,  with  regard  to 
the  non-fulfilment  of  the  second  necessary  condition,  viz. 
that  it  must  be  received  in  something,  we  notice  that  its 

1  Cf.  Nys,  op.  cit.,  pp.  216-287. 


PLACE  AND  SPACE  93 

outside  surface  would  afford  a  receptacle  for  it ;  for  this, 
though  only  modally  distinct  from  the  thing  itself,  is  yet 
sufficiently  distinct  for  our  purpose,  since  this  surface  can 
be  considered  as  a  container  instead  of  part  of  the  content ; 
and  we  are  all  agreed  that  space  is  not  a  receptacle,  which  is  a 
reality,  on  its  own  account,  apart  from  the  bodies  which  it 
contains. 

(b)  We  turn,  therefore,  to  the  second  way  of  regarding 
space  as  an  interval  of  distance.  This  is  that  space  is  form- 
ally constituted  by  the  dimensions  of  the  containing  body 
in  so  far  as  the  relation  of  distance  is  considered  in  them. 
This  theory  follows  directly  from  the  idea  of  space  as  the 
receptacle  of  bodies  ;  since  a  receptacle  of  a  body  is  that 
whose  dimensions  are  of  sufficient  extent  to  circumscribe  it  : 
so  that  space  will  be  constituted  by  the  dimensions  of  the 
containing  body,  considered  as  enclosing  an  extension,  i.e. 
precisely  with  reference  to  the  relation  of  extension. 

What  may  be  considered  to  be  a  serious  objection  to  this 
theory  is  that  it  makes  the  existence  of  the  void  not  only 
physically,  but  even  metaphysically  impossible  ;  for  it  is 
clear  that  a  body  cannot  contain  nothing  ;  since  to  assert 
this  would  be  equivalent  to  saying  that  it  does  not  contain — 
it  is  not  a  receptacle — which  is  to  deny  the  initial  concept  of 
space.  Hence,  in  a  void  space  would  vanish,  and  with  space 
distance.  So,  if  two  bodies  were  separated  by  a  void,  they 
would  be  separated  by  no  distance,  and  so  would  not  be 
separated  ;  so  that  the  existence  of  a  void  becomes  meta- 
physically impossible. 

On  the  Void. 

This  question  of  the  void  has  been  one  of  the  most  con- 
stantly discussed  problems  in  the  history  of  natural  philo- 
sophy, and  it  is  therefore  worth  while  examining  it  a  little 
more  fully.  Both  Plato  and  Aristotle  rejected  the  idea  that 
there  is,  in  fact,  any  empty  space  in  the  world  :  and  the 
latter  seems  to  have  regarded  it  as  impossible  that  there 
should  be.  Most  of  his  arguments  are  based  on  his  mistaken 
idea  of  '  natural  movement  '  ;  according  to  which  '  light  ' 
and  '  heavy  '  are  qualities  belonging  to  different  kinds  of 


94  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

bodies,  so  that  some  bodies  naturally  move  upwards,  others 
downwards  ;  and  both  these,  and  his  other,  arguments  are 
all  directed  to  show  that  it  is  physically  impossible  that  there 
should  be  a  vacuum.  S.  Thomas,  as  it  seems,  shared  these 
views,  and  even  added  one  reason  which  might  be  taken  to 
mean  that  he  regarded  a  vacuum  as  metaphysically  impos- 
sible, for  he  says  :  '  Cum  de  ratione  vacui  sit,  quod  sit  sfiatium 
corporis  prater  corpora,  sequitur  quod  vacuum  non  sit ,J — in 
other  words,  the  notion  of  a  vacuum  is  self-contradictory. 
Since,  however,  in  the  whole  of  this  section,  the  view  of  the 
Platonists,  which  he  regards  as  mistaken,  is  being  considered, 
it  is  not  clear  that  this  statement  should  be  taken  absolutely, 
but  it  may  be  only  '  ad  hominem.'  The  absolute  impossi- 
bility of  a  vacuum  was,  without  doubt,  of  necessity  main- 
tained by  Descartes,  since  he  identifies  extension  with  body, 
so  that  any  extension  will  be  ipso  facto  corporeal.  He  was 
followed  in  this  view  by  Spinoza  and  Balmes,  and  also  by 
Leibniz,  though  for  a  different  reason.2 

Apart  from  the  false  Cartesian  presuppositions  as  to  the 
nature  of  body,  it  is  clear  that  if  the  material  universe  is 
finite,  an  hypothesis  which  is  faced  by  no  metaphysical  con- 
tradiction, there  must  be  a  certain  kind  of  void  outside  it, 
which  some  call  a  negative  void  ;  so  that  a  void  is  possible, 
absolutely  speaking.  The  discussion  here,  however,  is  con- 
cerned with  the  possibility  of  a  void  within  the  confines  of 
the  material  universe,  and  regarding  the  matter  without 
prejudice,  there  seems  to  be  no  conclusive  reason  for  saying 
that  such  a  void  is  impossible  ;  since  it  would  only  imply 
that  there  should  be  no  matter  within  a  certain  area,  this 
area  remaining,  nevertheless,  surrounded  by  bodies.  Against 
this  it  is  argued  :  (i)  that  in  this  case  the  interior  surfaces  of 
the  body  (or  bodies)  which  surrounded  the  void  would  come 
together,  or  (2)  if  not,  at  least  there  would  be  no  determinate 
distance  across  the  void.  The  first  consequence  clearly  does 
not  follow,  since  bodies  are  not  kept  apart  by  the  matter 
which  separates  them,  but  simply  are  apart  by  being 
localised  at  different  points  in  space.  Neither  is  the  second 
a  necessary  consequence  of  a  void,  for  since,  if  there  was  one 

1  IV  Phys.,  Lect.  10,  No.  8.  2  Cf.  Nys,  op.  cit.,  p.  386. 


PLACE  AND  SPACE  95 

there  would  be  a  determinate  circumference  round  it,  there 
would  also  be  a  determinate  distance  diametrically  across  it. 
We  are,  then,  led  to  the  conclusion  that  an  internal  void  is 
possible. 

Whether  there  is,  in  fact,  any  void  within  the  material 
universe  is  a  question  which  is  even  less  easily  answered. 
Generally  speaking,  physicists  from  the  time  of  Aristotle 
down  to  the  present  day  have  agreed  in  saying  that  there  is 
not.  The  pre-Newtonian  scientists  held  this  opinion,  either 
on  the  grounds  put  forward  by  Aristotle,  or  later,  on  the 
basis  of  the  Cartesian  mechanics.  Even  when  this  latter 
view  was  not  accepted  in  its  entirety,  a  void  was  rejected,  as 
it  was  by  Newton,  on  the  ground  of  the  impossibility  of 
action  at  a  distance.  Consequently,  modern  scientists  have 
supposed  that  there  is  an  all-pervading  ether,  which  acts  as 
the  carrier  of  light,  and  electro-magnetic,  waves.  Even 
though,  in  the  universe  of  Einstein,  the  hypothesis  of  a 
luminiferous  ether  is  no  longer  necessary,  its  place  will  be 
taken  by  Space-Time.  It  would,  nevertheless,  be  unwise  to 
build  up  a  philosophical  theory  on  the  basis  of  these  specu- 
lations, and  therefore  rash  to  assert,  on  their  authority,  that 
there  is  no  void  in  the  material  universe.  In  any  case,  it 
seems  clear  that  a  theory  which  makes  the  void  metaphysic- 
ally impossible  cannot  be  regarded  as  a  satisfactory  account 
of  the  nature  of  space.  If,  then,  the  second  view,  given 
above,  is  to  be  taken  literally,  it  is  ruled  out ;  and  it  seems 
that  a  modification  of  the  first  view  is  required.  We  wish, 
then,  to  construct  a  theory  which  will  allow  of  a  single  body 
(if  there  were  only  one  in  the  universe)  being  spatial  or  in 
space,  since  there  seems  to  be  no  valid  reason  for  denying 
that  it  would  be  :  and,  secondly,  to  eliminate  the  intrinsic 
localising  accidents  which,  according  to  the  first  theory,  are 
the  foundations  of  the  relation  of  distance  which  constitutes 
space,  while  admitting  with  this  theory,  or  at  least  not 
excluding,  the  possibility  of  a  vacuum.  To  satisfy  these 
conditions,  we  shall  refuse  to  say  that  space  is  a  relation  of 
distance  between  several  bodies,  and  at  the  same  time  admit 
that  it  is  a  relation,  not  something  absolute,  as  the  second 
theory  maintains.    It  will,  therefore,  be  a  relation  which  will 


96  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

hold  as  well  in  a  single  body  as  in  several.  Moreover,  there 
is  no  doubt  that  the  basis  of  our  concept  of  space  is  extension. 
Hence,  it  will  be  a  relation  of  extension  or  distance.  Now,  it 
is  clear  that  the  only  relation  of  distance  which  is  to  be  found 
in  a  single  body  is  that  between  its  extremities  ;  and  space 
being  conceived  as  the  receptacle  of  body,  it  will  be,  as  it 
were,  an  envelope  enclosing  the  extremities  of  the  body,  and 
will  be  formally  constituted  by  the  three-dimensional  rela- 
tion of  distance  between  the  extremities  of  real  body.  Thus, 
from  the  point  of  view  of  the  concept  which  we  form  of  it, 
space  will  be  distinct  from  the  body  which  it  encloses,  though, 
in  fact,  their  extent  will  be  the  same,  and  an  empty  space 
will  be  identical  in  extent  with  the  interior  dimensions  of  the 
bodies  which  enclose  it.  This  explanation  thus  seems  to 
include  all  the  data  which  we  have  as  to  the  nature  of  space, 
for  it  will  be  a  receptacle  of  real  bodies,  it  will  be  found  as  the 
container  of  a  single  body,  and  empty  space  will  be  not 
impossible  ;  being  constituted  by  the  relation  of  distance 
between  the  extremities  of  the  real  body  or  bodies  which 
enclose  it.  The  space  of  a  single  body  (if  there  were  only 
one)  would  be  constituted  by  the  relation  of  distance  between 
its  own  extremities,  considered  ideally  as  enveloping  or  con- 
taining it.  It  is  clear  that,  if  this  view  be  taken,  space  will 
be  a  logical  being,  not  a  reality  on  its  own  account  ;  having, 
nevertheless,  a  basis  in  reality,  since  there  is,  in  nature,  real 
extension,  or  continuous  quantity.  The  relation  of  distance, 
as  conceived  of,  is  not  however  found  in  nature,  and  is  the 
absence  of  contact,  a  condition  which  is  verified  both  in  a 
vacuum  and  a  plenum.  That  space  is  indeed  such  a  logical 
being  is  very  generally  held  by  Scholastics. 

Section  III.     On  the  Occupation  of  Space, 
(a)  On  Impenetrability. 

If  one  body  occupies  a  portion  of  space  in  such  a  way  as 
to  fill  it,  it  seems  clear  that  it  will  exclude  another  from 
occupying  the  same  portion.  We  are  familiar  enough  with 
such  impenetrability  in  ordinary  life,  for  we  know  that  we 
cannot  occupy  the  same  place  as  another  man,  or  any  other 
solid  object.     The  question,  considered  philosophically,  is, 


PLACE  AND   SPACE  97 

however,  much  wider  than  this,  since  it  is  the  question 
whether  it  is  possible  for  two  bodies  to  occupy  the  same 
place  at  the  same  time,  i.e.  whether  compenetration  is 
possible.  Thus,  we  are  not  concerned  with  what  is  usually 
known  as  penetrability,  which  occurs  when  one  body  enters 
into  the  pores  or  interstices  of  another,  as  when  a  sponge  is 
filled  with  water  ;  for,  in  this  case,  the  body  which  is  pene- 
trated does  not  occupy  the  space  of  its  interstices,  and  there- 
fore there  is  no  question  of  two  bodies  occupying  the  same 
place.  Nor  is  our  question  confined  to  any  particular  kind 
of  bodies,  such  as  solids  or  liquids,  but  is  quite  general, 
relating  to  any  kind  of  bodies.1 

As  a  preliminary  to  dealing  with  the  possibility  of  com- 
penetration, something  must  be  said  as  to  the  question  of 
fact ;  viz.  whether  it  is  a  fact  that  any  matter  is  continuous, 
for  if  it  is  not,  the  whole  question  of  the  possibility  of  com- 
penetration falls  to  the  ground,  since  it  is  clear  that  if  no 
body  has  continuous  extension,  none  will  occupy  a  place,  so 
that  we  cannot  ask  whether  any  other  can  occupy  it  at  the 
same  time. 

That  the  question  comes  to  be  asked  at  all  is  due  to  current 
physical  theories,  in  which  matter  is  regarded  as  composed 
of  discontinuous  molecules,  molecules  of  discontinuous  atoms, 
atoms  of  discontinuous  electrons  and  protons.  The  electrons 
within  the  atom  are  said  to  be  such  that  they  cannot  have 
both  velocity  and  position  in  an  exact  sense.2  It  seems, 
therefore,  that  they  cannot  have  continuous  extension,  and 
the  same  would  be  true,  no  doubt,  of  the  nucleus  ;  and  so, 
in  this  theory,  all  continuous  extension  appears  to  be  taken 
away  from  the  world.3  On  the  other  hand,  we  have  a  theory 
which  is  the  antithesis  of  this,  and  asserts  that  all  through 
the  universe  there  is  an  absolutely  continuous  ether  which 

1  Fr.  McWilliams  in  his  Cosmology  (p.  94)  says  that  compenetration 
.  .  .  means  the  presence  together  of  two  absolutely  solid  bodies  in  the  same 
place.'  If  this  were  to  be  taken  to  mean  that  the  question  is  confined  to 
solids,  as  opposed  to  liquids  or  gases,  it  would  no  doubt  be  a  mistake. 
But  the  context  seems  to  show  that  his  meaning  is  that  the  question  does 
not  relate  to  solids  in  this  sense,  but  to  continuous  bodies,  or,  to  the  parts 
of  discontinuous,  or  porous  ones,  which  are  continuous. 

2  Eddington,  Nature  of  the  Physical  World,  pp.  220  ff. 

3  Cf.  Whitehead,  Science  and  the  Modern  World,  pp.  122  ff. 


98  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

is  thought  of  as  the  carrier  of  light,  and  electro-magnetic 
waves.  This  ether  pervades  the  atom,  and  even  the  nucleus 
and  electron  of  which  the  atom  is  composed.  These,  then, 
may  be  either  knots  or  coagulations  in  the  ether  itself,  in 
which  case  there  would  be  only  one  body  in  the  world — the 
ether — and  so  no  chance  of  compenetration  ;  or  else  they 
may  be  bodies  other  than  the  ether,  in  which  case  compene- 
tration is  a  fact.  Science,  therefore,  in  different  moods,  or 
in  accordance  with  different  theories,  seems  to  say  :  (i)  that 
the  question  of  compenetration  is  illegitimate,  since  there 
are  no  extended  bodies,  i.e.  having  continuous  extension, 
(2)  that  it  cannot  occur,  since  there  is  one  continuously 
extended  body,  and  only  one,  and  (3)  that  it  does  occur. 
The  apparent  contradictions  here  are  reconciled  by  taking 
now  one  view  of  matter,  now  another ;  and  by  denying 
material  character  to  the  ether.1  This  last  denial  would 
clear  up  the  affair,  if  we  knew  what  matter  itself  is,  for  it  is 
clear  that  we  cannot  attach  any  meaning  to  the  statement  : 
'  the  ether  is  not  material,'  unless  we  know  what  the  predi- 
cate means.  Now,  this  is  just  what  we  do  not  know  ;  and 
we  therefore  have  to  be  content  to  use  that  theory  which 
suits  us  best,  i.e.  which  is  simplest,  in  investigating  any 
particular  class  of  phenomena.  But  whatever  may  be  the 
divergences  of  view  as  to  the  nature  of  matter  and  the  ether, 
all  the  theories  agree  in  making  the  elements  of  matter 
separate  from  one  another  in  space,  i.e.  in  saying  that  there 
is  a  distance  or  extension  between  them.  Now,  it  is  clear 
that  if  the  ether  were  supposed  to  be  material,  we  should 
have  a  number  of  continuously  extended  portions  of  it ; 
and  so  some  continuous  body  in  the  universe  ;  and  if  it  is 
not  material,  it  is  impossible  to  measure  it  by  physical  means, 
since  all  our  measuring  instruments  are,  of  necessity, 
material ;  so  that  it  would  be  illegitimate  to  assert  that  it  is 
extended.  It  seems  to  be  a  curious  position  to  deny  exten- 
sion to  material  objects  which  can  be  measured,  and  to 
assert  it  of  an  immaterial  one  which  cannot.  From  the 
point  of  view  of  physics,  therefore,  the  position  is  not  unsatis- 
factory, for  we  can  use  any  hypothesis  which  suits  us  at  the 

1  Cf.  Eddington,  op.  cit.,  pp.  31  f. 


PLACE  AND  SPACE  99 

moment ;  but  from  the  point  of  view  of  philosophy,  if  these 
hypotheses  are  to  be  taken  as  telling  us  of  the  nature  of 
bodies,  it  is  intolerable,  and  lands  us  in  contradictions  ;  and 
our  only  course  would  be  to  deny  any  extension  at  all  to  the 
physical  world  ;  since  it  is  absurd  to  assert  that  unextended 
points,  having  no  position,  are  separated  from  one  another 
in  space.  If  bodies,  or  their  elements,  are  not  extended, 
the  spaces  between  them  cannot  be  either.  In  this  case, 
however,  we  are  faced  with  the  insuperable  difficulty  of 
explaining  the  illusion  of  extension,  as  it  is  then  thought  to 
be,  and  all  the  other  difficulties  of  the  Leibnizian  theory. 
We  are  therefore  compelled  to  reject  the  notion  that  there  is 
no  extension  in  the  world,  and  to  assert  the  continuous 
extension  of  both  simple  and  compound  bodies,  unless  such 
extension  can  be  shown  not  to  exist  in  a  particular  case.  In 
doing  so,  we  shall  not  be  rejecting  the  scientific  theories,  as 
scientific,  i.e.  as  giving  the  simplest  and  most  comprehensive 
account  of  phenomena  yet  discovered,  but  we  shall  be  reject- 
ing them  as  philosophical  ones,  which  they  were  never 
intended  to  be  :  and  we  do  so  for  the  excellent  reason  that 
they  are,  in  this  sense,  contradictory  in  themselves,  and  lead 
to  impossible  conclusions.  If  it  be  true,  then,  that  some 
bodies  have  continuous  extension,  it  is  possible  to  ask 
whether  two  of  them  can  occupy,  i.e.  make  their  dimensions 
exactly  correspond  with  the  same  place  at  the  same  time. 
That  they  actually  do  so,  and  therefore,  that  it  is  possible  for 
them  to  do  so,  is  held  by  some  scientists,  as  Lodge,  who  con- 
sider that  the  ether  is  a  kind  of  matter  which  permeates  other 
bodies  j1  but  there  is  here  almost  certainly  some  confusion 
of  ideas.  Among  philosophers,  apart  from  the  Dynamists, 
who  deny  the  legitimacy  of  the  question,  none  hold  that 
bodies  actually  do  compenetrate,  and  almost  all  that  it  is  in 
some  way,  either  physically  or  metaphysically,  impossible 
for  them  to  do  so. 

Descartes  and  his  school  necessarily  thought  that  it  is 
metaphysically  impossible,   for,   if  the  nature  of  body  is 

1  Cf.  Lodge,  Ether  and  Reality,  Ch.  II,  pp.  38  ff.  Though  he  seems  to 
deny  that  the  ether  is  '  matter,'  yet  he  says  that  material  particles  are 
probably  formed  out  of  it.  So  the  ether  is  other  than  the  particles,  and 
yet  the  particles  consist  of  ether. 


ioo         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

extension,  where  there  is  a  single  extension  there  must  be  a 
single  body,  so  that  two  bodies  occupying  the  same  place 
would  ipso  facto  be  one  :  in  other  words,  the  supposition  is 
unthinkable. 

Locke  thinks  it  physically  impossible,  since  '  this  resis- 
tance, whereby  it  '  (i.e.  a  body)  '  keeps  other  bodies  out  of 
the  space  which  it  possesses,  is  so  great,  that  no  force,  how 
great  soever,  can  surmount  it.'1 

Though  among  Scholastics  there  is  general  agreement  as 
to  the  possibility,  absolutely  speaking,  of  compenetration, 
there  is  considerable  difference  of  opinion  as  to  the  nature  of 
that  property  of  bodies  which  makes  them  naturally  impene- 
trable. Some  consider  it  to  be  an  active  force,  as  Palmieri 
and  Hoenen,  others  as  a  simple  consequence  of  continuous 
extension  ;  and  this  latter  opinion  is  that  of  the  majority, 
following  S.  Thomas.  Indeed,  this  view  seems  much  more 
consonant  both  with  common  sense  and  the  present  state  of 
knowledge  than  the  other  ;  with  common  sense,  since  it  is 
difficult  to  see  how  a  body  can  preserve  an  unbroken  con- 
tinuity of  its  boundaries  if  another  one,  which  is  also  con- 
tinuous, forces  its  way  into  it ;  and  with  our  knowledge  of 
nature,  for  in  fact  no  compenetration  is  known  in  nature, 
but  only  the  passage  of  small  bodies  through  the  pores  of 
other  bodies,  and,  moreover,  the  smallest  scientific  bodies, 
atoms  and  electrons  (a-particles ,  etc.)  are  said  to  vary  in  their 
power  of  penetration.  So  the  a,  (3,  and  y  rays  are  progres- 
sively more  penetrating,  and  this  in  proportion  as  they 
possess  more  of  the  character  of  waves,  and  less  of  corpuscles. 
This  would  seem  to  accord  better  with  the  idea  that  the  cause 
of  impenetrability  is  the  corpuscular  or  continuous  nature  of  a 
body  rather  than  the  activity  exerted  by  the  body  to  be 
penetrated. 

Whatever  interpretation  is  to  be  put  upon  the  facts,  in  so 
far  as  they  are  known,  philosophical  considerations  seem 
clearly  to  indicate  that  impenetrability  naturally  results 
from  the  extension  of  bodies  ;  since  if,  as  we  have  seen,  it  is 

1  Locke,  An  Essay  concerning  Human  Understanding,  Bk.  II,  Ch.  IV, 
Sect.  3.  Fr.  Dario,  S.J.,  and  Fr.  Hugon,  O.P.,  represent  Locke  as  holding 
it  to  be  metaphysically  impossible,  but  this  does  not  seem  to  be  the  case. 
Vide  Dario,  Cosmologia,  p.  143  ;   Hugon,  Cursus  Phil.,  Vol.  II,  p.  197. 


PLACE  AND   SPACE  101 

the  function  of  quantity  to  give  material  substance  parts 
outside  parts,  it  will  naturally  follow  that  one  part  will  be 
outside  the  place  of  another.  Now,  this  relationship  of  the 
parts  of  quantity  with  regard  to  place  is  evidently  something 
extrinsic  to  quantity  itself,  since  the  nature  of  quantity  is 
merely  to  have  parts  outside  parts  in  the  whole,  without 
reference  to  place.  Consequently,  absolutely  speaking,  no 
contradiction  is  involved  in  this  natural  consequence  of 
quantity,  which  is  impenetrability,  being  removed  ;  for  the 
essential  character  of  quantity,  the  having  parts  outside 
parts  would  still  remain,  even  though  the  parts  of  the  quan- 
tities of  the  two  bodies  would  occupy  the  same  place.  Hence 
compenetration,  though  naturally  impossible,  is  not  meta- 
physically so,  and  consequently  could  be  effected  by  an 
agent  who  had  sufficient  power,  such  as  God  ;  granted  that 
the  distinction  of  the  bodies,  which  is  ordinarily  secured  by 
distinction  of  place,  could  be  preserved  ;  a  condition  which 
is  capable  of  fulfilment  in  the  case  of  bodies  of  different 
material  constitution  ;  though  impossible  for  purely  geo- 
metrical volumes,  which,  if  equal,  can  only  be  distinguished 
by  position. 

(b)  On  Multilocation. 

If  two  bodies  cannot  naturally  be  in  one  place  together  ; 
what  is  to  be  said  on  the  question  whether  one  body 
can  be  in  two  or  more  places  simultaneously  ?  Is  such 
multilocation  possible  ?  This  question  admits  of  solu- 
tion much  more  easily  than  the  last.  We  must  bear 
in  mind  the  distinction  made  above  (pp.  81  f.)  between 
circumscriptive  and  non-circumscriptive  presence  in  a 
place.  That  non-circumscriptive  presence  (which,  as  we 
have  seen,  is  only  analogically  called  location)  by  a 
thing  in  several  places  at  once,  is  possible,  is  universally 
admitted,  for  there  is  clearly  no  contradiction  involved  in  a 
body  being  circumscriptively  in  one  place,  and  yet  joined  to 
another  in  some  other  way.  With  regard  to  circumscriptive 
presence,  on  the  contrary,  there  is  a  difference  of  opinion,  for 
Suarez  holds  that  it  is  not  absolutely  or  metaphysically 
impossible,  in  which  view  he  is  followed  by  Dario,  among 


102         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

recent  writers.  The  opinion  of  S.  Thomas  is  quite  clear, 
since  he  says  plainly  that  bilocation  involves  a  contradiction, 
which  is  to  say  that  it  is  metaphysically  impossible.1  The 
reason  for  this  latter  view  seems  absolutely  convincing,  since 
it  is  quite  impossible  for  a  thing,  while  retaining  its  own 
dimensions  to  be  twice,  or  three  times,  as  large  as  it  is. 
That  this  would  be  the  case,  if  a  body  were  circumscriptively 
in  more  than  one  place  at  the  same  time,  is  clear,  since  cir- 
cumscriptive location  is  brought  about  by  the  dimensions  of 
the  located  body  corresponding  with  those  of  the  containing 
one  ;  so  that  if  a  body  were  in  several  places  at  once,  its 
dimensions  would  correspond  with  those  of  several  contain- 
ing bodies  at  once  ;  and  its  dimension,  say  A,  would  be  at 
the  same  time  A  +  B,  .  .  .  which  is  contrary  to  the 
principle  of  identity.  If  we  want  to  bring  this  vividly  before 
the  imagination,  we  may  picture  a  man  sitting  in  two  con- 
tiguous places  at  once.  The  space  occupied  by  him  would 
thus  be  double  what  it  was  when  he  was  sitting  in  the  usual 
way,  and  yet  his  dimensions  would  remain  the  same,  and  so 
could  not  occupy  more  space  than  they  did  before.  Without 
swelling  out  he  is  twice  as  big,  which  is  absurd. 

1  Quodlibet  III,  Arts,  i  and  2  ;   IV  Sent.  dist.  XLIV,  Q.  2,  a,  2,  sol.  3, 

ad  4um. 


CHAPTER  VII 

THE   LIMITS   OF   QUANTITY 

The  Infinite — Its  Kinds — The  Possibility  of  Actually  Infinite 
Quantity — Of  an  Actually  Infinite  Multitude. 

One  question  still  remains  to  be  discussed  with  reference  to 
quantity,  viz.  whether  it  is  necessarily  limited,  or  is  it 
possible  for  it  to  be  infinite  ;  for  the  infinite  is  that  which 
has  no  term  or  limit.  In  order  to  grasp  the  exact  bearing  of 
this  question,  we  must  first  see  the  various  ways  in  which 
this  term  '  infinite  '  can  be  understood. 

1.  So  the  Scholastics  distinguish  in  the  first  place  between 
the  privative  and  negative  infinite,  the  former  being  that 
which,  though  capable  of  being  terminated,  yet  is  not  actually 
terminated  ;  while  the  latter  is  that  which  is  incapable  of 
being  terminated  ;  which  incapacity  may  be  due  to  its  entire 
perfection,  when  we  have  what  is  sometimes  known  as  the 
positive  infinite  (or  to  its  imperfection). 

2.  Again,  they  divide  the  infinite  into  the  categorematical 
and  syncategorematical.  The  first  is  that  which  is  unlimited 
in  act,  and  so  is  called  the  actual  infinite  ;  and  the  second, 
that  which  is  capable  of  receiving  one  act  after  another 
without  end.  So  it  is  finite  in  act,  and  infinite  potentially 
only,  and  is  called  the  potential  infinite,  or  the  indefinite. 

3.  A  third  division  is  into  the  infinite  simply  speaking, 
and  in  some  particular  respect  (secundum  quid).  The  infinite 
simply  speaking  is  that  which  is  altogether  unlimited,  and 
possesses  every  possible  perfection.  It  is  known  also  as  the 
absolute  infinite.  The  infinite  secundum  quid  is  that  which 
in  some  direction  has  no  term,  and  thus  possesses  some  par- 
ticular perfection  in  an  unlimited  degree.  This  is  also  called 
the  relative  infinite. 

The  question  we  are  asking  here  is  whether  it  is  possible 
to  have  an  actual  infinite  with  respect  to  quantity. 

103 


104         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

That  the  syncategorematical  infinite,  both  in  magnitude 
and  multitude,  is  possible,  is  sufficiently  clear,  for  no  reason 
can  be  assigned  why  we  should  stop  at  any  particular  magni- 
tude in  a  series,  and  say  there  could  not  be  a  greater  ;  and  the 
same  applies  to  a  series  of  individuals — there  could  always 
be  one  more  ;  and  we  have  seen,  too,  that  the  continuum  is 
divisible  to  infinity.  Our  question,  therefore,  is  confined  to 
the  possibility  of  the  categorematical  infinite. 

Aristotle  defines  the  privative  infinite,  of  which  we  are 

here  Speaking,  as  follows  :  arrtipov  /i«v  ovv  «rriv  ov  xaT<* 
Trocruv    kaLjifidvovo-iv    cuei     ti     \af3elv    ccttiv     e£o)     (207a7)»1     which 

may  be  rendered  :  '  so  then  the  infinite  is  that  of  which 
any  quantity  being  taken,  there  always  remains  some- 
thing to  be  taken  outside  '  (this  quantity)  ;  a  definition 
which  is  approved  of  by  S.  Thomas,  who  rejects  with 
Aristotle  the  definition  of  infinity  which  makes  it  '  that 
outside  which  there  is  nothing  '  :  since  what  is  essential  to 
infinity  is  that  it  should  be  inexhaustible,  not  that  there 
should  be  nothing  greater  than  it.  It  has  been  suggested2 
that  this  is  rather  the  definition  of  the  indefinite,  but  this 
does  not  seem  to  be  the  case,  for  in  the  indefinite,  when  a  part 
has  been  taken,  there  does  not  remain  something  more  to  be 
taken,  but  only  something  potential ;  and  it  is  that  which  is 
potentially,  not  actually,  inexhaustible. 

There  is  no  general  agreement  as  to  the  possibility  of  an 
actually  infinite  magnitude  and  multitude  within  the  genus  of 
quantity,  but  the  majority  of  Scholastics  following  Aristotle 
and  S.  Thomas  deny  the  possibility  of  either. 

(a)  That  an  actually  infinite  discrete  quantity,  or  number, 
is  impossible,  is  easily  seen,  since  every  actual  number  is 
closed  by  its  last  unit,  for  if  it  had  not  a  last  unit,  it  would 
not  be  actual  but  potential ;  as  the  series  of  ordinal  numbers, 
ij  2,  3,  4,  etc.  ...  w.  is  a  potential  whole,  not  an  actual 
one  ;  and  so  is  potentially  infinite,  or  indefinite,  not  actually 
infinite.  What  is  actually  infinite  cannot  be  closed  by  a  last 
unit,  or  it  would  not  be  infinite,  and  consequently  no  number 
can  be  actually  infinite. 

1  Cf.  S.  Thomas  in  III  Phys.,  Lect.  II. 

2  Vide  Dario,  Cosmologia,  p.  114. 


THE  LIMITS  OF  QUANTITY  105 

(b)  Turning  to  the  question  of  an  actually  infinite  con- 
tinuous quantity,  or  magnitude,  we  notice  that  this  might 
be  an  attribute  either  of  natural  or  mathematical  body. 
But  it  can  be  seen  that  the  supposition  that  either  has  such 
an  attribute  leads  to  contradiction. 

1.  Considering  natural  body,  we  see  that  its  quantity  is 
an  intrinsic  accident,  which  will  therefore  take  its  rise  from  its 
substantial  form,  since  it  is  this  which  gives  a  thing  its 
intrinsic  nature.  Now,  it  is  clear  that  every  natural  body, 
when  it  is  actual,  will  have  a  certain  determined  substantial 
form,  since  form  is  its  act,  and  that  a  determined  form  cannot 
be  the  source  of  what  is  not  determined,  but  infinite.  Hence, 
no  natural  body  can  have  an  actually  infinite  extension  or 
quantity. 

2.  Just  as  natural  body,  when  actual,  has  a  certain  deter- 
mined form,  so  has  mathematical  body,  though,  in  this  case, 
the  form  is  its  shape.  Now,  shape  is  the  outline  of  the 
mathematical  figure,  and  is  therefore  its  termination  or 
boundary.  Consequently,  every  mathematical  body  is  ter- 
minated and  finite,  and  the  supposition  that  it  is  not,  is  in 
contradiction  with  the  very  notion  of  mathematical 
body.1 

We  see,  then,  that  it  is  impossible  to  find  actual  infinity 
either  in  number  (multitude  within  the  genus  of  quantity), 
or  in  magnitude. 

Though,  strictly  speaking,  we  are  here  concerned  only  with 
the  possibility  of  an  actually  infinite  quantity  ;  since  we 
have  spoken  several  times  of  multitude  within  the  genus  of 
quantity,  it  is  implied  that  we  might  have  a  multitude  outside 
that  genus,  and  the  question  suggests  itself  whether  such  a 
multitude  could  be  actually  infinite  ;  so  that  it  is  convenient 
to  discuss  it  here. 

By  a  multitude  we  mean  a  collection  of  distinct  beings  ;  if 
these  are  quantitative,  it  will  be  a  multitude  within  the  genus 
of  quantity  ;  if  not,  it  will  be  outside  it.  Now,  quantity  is 
an  accident  found  only  in  material  substances,  so  that  a 
collection  of  quantitative  beings  will  be  a  collection  of  material 
ones.     Hence,  the  question  here  asked  is  whether  we  can 

1  Cf.  S.  Thomas,  Summa  Theol.,  Pars  I,  Q.  7,  a.  3. 


106         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

have  a  collection  of  immaterial  beings  which  is  actually 
infinite. 

The  earlier  Thomists,  as  Capreolus,1  affirm  that  the  notion 
of  an  actually  infinite  multitude  involves  an  intrinsic  contra- 
diction ;  and  this  seems  to  have  been  the  generally  accepted 
view  among  the  great  Thomist  writers,  such  as  John  of 
S.  Thomas  ;2  though  there  is  always  much  doubt  whether 
they  are  not  speaking  only  of  quantitative  multitude.  In 
any  case  many  recent  writers,  as  Hugon,3  are  definitely 
opposed  to  the  possibility  of  any  kind  of  actually  infinite 
multitude.  Nevertheless,  the  contrary  view  has  lately  begun 
to  find  favour,  as  with  Mercier,4  Nys,5  Remer,6  and  Geny. 

The  opinion  of  S.  Thomas  is  not  altogether  clear,  but  it 
seems  that  we  can  trace  a  development  of  his  thought  in 
this  matter.  In  the  Summa  he  denies  the  possibility  of  an 
actually  infinite  multitude.7  This  was  written8  in  the  years 
1 267-1 268.  Nevertheless,  the  argument  on  which  he  founds 
this  assertion  is  pronounced  by  him,  two  years  earlier,  in  his 
commentary  on  the  Physics  (III  Phys.,  Lect.  8,  circa  1265) 
to  be  a  probable  one  only.  Thus  it  is  not  surprising  to  find 
that  in  the  Questiones  Quodlibetales  (IX,  a.  i,  XII,  a.  2), 
written  in  1264-1268,  he  distinguishes  between  the  absolute 
and  ordinated  power  of  God,  and  seems  to  allow  that,  with 
respect  to  the  former,  an  actually  infinite  multitude  is  not 
impossible,  though  he  says  that  the  view  which  denies  its 
possibility  '  seems  truer.'  Finally,  in  the  essay  De  JEternitate 
Mundi  (1270),  he  absolutely  p-^irms  that  no  proof  of  the 
impossibility  of  an  actually  infinite  multitude  has  yet  been 
given  :  '  Et  tamen  non  est  adhuc  demonstratum  quod  Deus  non 
possit  facer e  infinita  esse  in  actu.'  With  regard  to  the  state- 
ments in  the  Summa,  we  may  perhaps  apply  to  them  the 
distinction  made  in  the  Quodlibets,  and  say  that  they  '  should 

1  Capreolus  (ed.  Paban-Pegues),  Vol.  II,  p.  537. 

2  John  of  S.  Thomas,  Cursus  Phil.    Phil.  Nat.,  Part  I,  Q.  15,  a.  3. 
8  Hugon,  Cursus  Phil.,  Vol.  V,  pp.  193  ff. 

4  Mercier,  Metaphysique  Generate,  pp.  ic  ,  ff. 
6  Nys,  La  notion  d'Espace,  pp.  335  ff. 

6  Remer  and  Geny,  Cosmologia,  Nos.  119  ff. 

7  Summa  Theol.,  Pars  I,  Q.  7,  a.  4  ;  Pars  I,  Q.  7,  a.  3,  ad  411m  ;  1.46,2, 
ad  6  and  7. 

8  The  chronology  of  these  writings  is  that  of  Mandonnet,  Bibliographie 
Thomiste,  pp.  xii  ff . 


THE  LIMITS  OF  QUANTITY  107 

be  understood  not  absolutely,  having  regard  to  nothing  but 
the  power  of  God  which  is  limited  only  by  the  principle  of 
contradiction,  but  bearing  in  mind  the  normal  conditions  of 
quantitative  beings,  and  the  action  of  God,  which  pre- 
supposes the  concord  or  harmony  of  all  His  attributes.'1 

The  chief  argument  against  the  possibility  of  an  actually 
infinite  multitude  is  that  such  a  multitude  could  not  be  added 
to,  being  infinite,  and  yet  since  it  is  actually  infinite,  it 
must  contain  a  definite  number  of  individuals,  otherwise  it 
would  be  only  potentially  infinite,  not  actually  so  ;  it  would 
be  indefinite.  If,  however,  it  contains  a  definite  number  of 
individuals,  we  could  always  add  one  more  ;  so  that  it  both 
could  and  could  not  be  added  to,  which  is  absurd.  Further, 
if  we  supposed  that  there  existed  an  actually  infinite  multi- 
tude of  spiritual  beings,  there  would  be  a  still  greater  multi- 
tude of  their  thoughts,  volitions,  etc.,  so  that  we  should  have 
two  infinities  of  which  one  was  greater  than  the  other  ;  so 
that  the  lesser  could  not  be  infinite.  The  idea,  then,  of  an 
actually  infinite  multitude  is,  it  is  argued,  self-contradictory  ; 
since  such  a  multitude,  though  infinite,  must  contain  a 
definite,  i.e.  a  limited  or  finite,  number  of  individuals. 

The  fallacy  of  this  argument  seems  to  be  that  we  are  not 
here  dealing  with  individuals  which  are  numerable,  and  con- 
sequently the  idea  of  number  introduced  into  the  argument  is 
out  of  place. 

In  favour  of  the  possibility  it  is  argued  : 

1.  That  the  ideas  of  infinite  and  multitude  are  not  contra- 
dictory ;  since  the  second  implies  only  a  collection  of  dis- 
tinct individuals,  while  the  first  denies  that  this  collection 
has  any  limits. 

2.  God  knows  all  possible  things,  actually  and  distinctly. 
There  is,  however,  an  infinity  of  possibles,  so  that  God  knows 
an  actually  infinite  multitude,  distinctly  and  actually. 

3.  If  creation  from  eternity  is  possible,  there  seems  to  be 
no  reason  why  there  should  not  be  an  actual  infinity  of 
creatures.  This  series  would  be  infinite  a  parte  ante,  though 
limited  a  parte  post,  i.e.  at  the  '  now  '  ;  just  as  the  series  of 
our  thoughts  and  volitions,  on  the  hypothesis  of  individual 

1  Pegues,  Commentaire  Litterale  de  la  Somme  Thiol,  in  I. ,7, 3,  and  4. 


108         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

immortality,  is  infinite  a  parte  post,  though  limited  a  parte 
ante,  if  our  souls  were  created  at  our  conception. 

Whatever  is  to  be  said  on  this  difficult  problem,  we  must 
certainly  avoid  confusing  multitude  with  number.  As 
Cardinal  Mercier  says  :  '  The  question  of  the  possibility  of 
an  infinite  multitude  is  certainly  open  to  dispute,  but  the 
debate  cannot  be  cut  short  by  the  summary  consideration  that 
every  collection  of  unities  is  essentially  finite.  To  confuse 
multitude  and  number  is  to  solve  the  question  by  begging  it.'1 

Note  :  S.  Thomas  remarks  in  the  Contra  Gentiles  (Bk.  II, 
Ch.  81)  that  Aristotle  in  the  Physics  (III  Phys,  V,  13  ff.  : 
S.  Th.  Lect,  9),  and  in  the  De  Ccelo  et  Mundo  (I  De  Ccelo, 
V  ff.  ;  S.  Th.  Lect.  9  ff.),  proves  that  there  is  no  actually 
infinite  multitude  of  corporeal  beings,  but  not  that  there  is 
none  of  incorporeal  ones.  This  was  written  between  1258 
and  1260. 

1  Mercier,  Metaphysique  Generate,  p.  196. 


CHAPTER  VIII 

THE   QUALITY   OF   BODIES,   OR   MOTION 

The   Nature   of   Motion — Action   at   a   Distance — The    Nature   of 
Gravitational  Action. 

Section  I.  On  the  Nature  of  Motion. 
After  the  consideration  of  the  quantity  of  bodies,  we  now 
turn  to  that  of  their  common  quality,  which  is  change.  The 
word  '  motion  '  was  used  by  Aristotle  and  S.  Thomas  to 
express  this  ;  but  its  signification  is  evidently  not  the  same 
as  that  of  mutation,  or  the  transit  from  one  state  to  another, 
for  mutation  may  be  either  intrinsic  or  extrinsic  ;  and  in 
both  cases  there  are  some  kinds  of  mutation  which  cannot 
properly  be  called  motions.  For  extrinsic  mutation  may  be 
either  metaphysical,  as  creation  and  annihilation,  which  are 
not  motions  properly  speaking,  since  in  both  there  is  only 
one  term  :  or  physical.  In  this  latter  case  the  change  may 
be  either  substantial  or  accidental ;  the  first  being  of  two 
kinds :  generation  and  corruption ;  while  the  second 
embraces  both  instantaneous  change,  which  is  accidental 
generation  and  corruption,  and  which  again,  not  being  con- 
tinuous is  not  motion  properly  so  called  ;  as  well  as  succes- 
sive, which  includes  local  motion,  alteration,  and  increase  (or 
growth). 

Motion,  in  the  sense  of  successive  physical  mutation,  is 
defined  by  Aristotle  as  '  the  act  of  that  which  is  in  potency 
as  such.'1  Obviously,  when  a  thing  is  merely  in  potency  to 
something  it  has  not  begun  to  change  ;  when  it  is  actually 
something,  it  has  ceased  to  change,  if  it  ever  has  changed  ; 
so  that  in  order  that  it  may  be  in  motion  it  must  be  neither 
wholly  actual,  nor  wholly  potential,  but  in  some  intermediate 

1  III  Phys.,  i  ;    20iaio. 
109 


no         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

state,  i.e.  will  be  the  actualisation  of  that  which  is  in  potency, 
or  of  the  potential.  But  this  is  not  sufficient  for  actual 
present  change,  for  it  may  have  begun  a  motion  towards 
some  term,  and  never  attained  it,  but  have  stopped  half- 
way. In  this  case,  though  it  is  in  potency  to  the  term,  and 
in  process  of  being  actualised,  it  is  not  changing.  Hence, 
the  words  '  as  such  '  are  added  in  the  definition,  meaning 
that  the  potency  is  being  actualised,  or  is  actually  tending 
to  some  further  act.1 

Now  motion,  which  is  confined,  strictly  speaking,  to  that 
kind  of  change  which  is  successive — since,  as  S.  Thomas 
says,2  it  requires  time — is  always  produced  by  some  agent. 
So  we  are  led  to  the  consideration  of  action,  of  which  the 
correlative  is  called  '  passion.'  Action,  moreover,  is  of  two 
kinds  :  immanent,  whose  source  and  term  are  in  the  agent, 
and  transeunt,  which  produces  an  effect  in  something  other 
than  the  agent. 

There  was,  in  the  Middle  Ages,  a  vigorous  dispute  as  to 
the  subject  of  action,  some  maintaining  that  action  was  in 
the  agent,  others  that  it  was  in  the  thing  acted  on — the 
patient ;  the  first  view  being  held  by  the  Scotists,  Cajetan, 
and  others  ;  the  second  by  the  majority  of  Thomists,  such 
as  Capreolus,  and  by  Suarez.  It  is  not  necessary  for  us  to 
enter  in  detail  into  this  discussion,  which  seems  to  be  largely 
a  controversy  about  words  and  phrases  ;  since  Scholastics 
now  generally  agree  that  the  contending  views  can  be  recon- 
ciled, and  all  the  factors  of  the  situation  satisfactorily 
accounted  for,  by  saying  that  there  are  in  action  two  form- 
alities, one  by  which  the  agent  is  actuated,  and  another 
which  is  in  the  term,  and  actualises  the  patient ;  so  that  the 
complete  formula,  with  regard  to  the  subject  of  action,  will 
be  that  action  is  initially  in  the  agent,  and  completely  in  the 
patient.  It  is,  in  fact,  clear  that  the  agent  is  the  cause  of 
action,  and  originates  it ;  and  no  less  clear  that  it  is  the 
patient  which  is  altered,  and  so,  that  the  action,  as  producing 
its  effect,  which  is  action  properly  so  called,  is  in  the  patient. 
So  S.  Thomas  says  :  '  An  act,  which  is  in  reality  the  same, 
belongs  to  two  things  in  different  ways  :    for  it  belongs  to 

1  Cf.  Ross,  Aristotle,  p.  81.  2  V  Phys.,  I,  Lect.  i. 


THE  QUALITY  OF  BODIES  in 

the  agent  inasmuch  as  it  is  from  it,  and  to  the  patient 
inasmuch  as  it  is  in  it.'1 

Section  II.     On  Action  at  a  Distance. 

Having  determined  the  way  in  which  it  is  most  correct  to 
speak  of  the  subject  of  action,  we  next  have  to  consider  its 
necessary  conditions.  Now,  it  is  suggested  that  presence  is 
not  such  a  condition,  but  as  this  matter  has  given  rise  to  a 
good  deal  of  controversy,  it  is  well  to  see  what  can  be  said 
about  it. 

Preliminary  Notions. 

It  is  obvious  that  when  we  say  that  two  things  are  present 
to  one  another,  we  mean  that  they  are  not  separated  from 
one  another  in  some  particular  respect.  If  we  are  dealing 
with  quantitative  things,  this  non-separation,  with  regard  to 
quantity  or  extension,  is  called  contact. 

Now,  presence  is  of  two  kinds  :  virtual  and  formal ;  for, 
as  between  an  agent  and  its  effect,  it  may  happen,  either 
that  the  very  substance  of  the  agent  is  present  to  the  effect, 
when  we  have  formal  presence,  as  in  the  case  of  the  soul  and 
the  body  which  it  informs  ;  or  that  the  agent  is  present  to 
the  effect,  not  in  its  own  substance,  but  by  means  of  its 
power,  as  in  the  case  of  a  man  whose  thoughts  produce  effects 
in  others,  such  as  those  of  a  statesman,  a  philosopher,  or  a 
religious  teacher.  The  Scholastics  call  the  presence,  in  these 
two  cases,  immediacy  of  suppositum,  and  immediacy  of 
power,  respectively. 

Quantitative  presence  is  divided  in  a  similar  way.  So  we 
have  mass  contact  when  the  extremities  of  two  bodies  are 
together,  and  virtual  contact,  when  there  is  immediacy  of 
power  only,  between  two  things. 

It  is  clear  that  mass  contact  can  only  occur  in  the  case  of 
two  bodies,  whereas  there  may  be  virtual  contact  between 
two  things,  of  which  one  is  quantitative,  or  corporeal,  and 
the  other  not  quantitative,  or  spiritual. 

The  statement '  action  at  a  distance  is  impossible,'  may  be 
taken  in  one  or  other  of  two  senses  as  meaning  either  that  we 

1  III  Phys.   Lect.  5,  10. 


ii2  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

cannot  have  action  between  two  bodies  without  mass  con- 
tact, or  that  such  action  is  impossible  without  either  mass  or 
virtual  contact.  The  word  '  cannot '  is  also  ambiguous,  since 
it  may  imply  physical  impossibility,  i.e.  that  we  have  no 
warrant  in  nature  for  saying  that  it  can  occur,  or  meta- 
physical and  absolute  impossibility.  How  easy  it  is  to  con- 
fuse these  meanings  can  be  seen  in  a  remark  by  Dr.  Schiller  : 
'  Such  action  '  (i.e.  at  a  distance)  '  our  scientists  persist  in 
regarding  as  impossible.  ...  If  metaphysics  had  been  con- 
sulted, it  would  have  been  obvious  that  no  special  medium 
was  required  to  make  interaction  possible  between  bodies 
that  coexist,  seeing  that  their  coexistence  is  an  ample 
guarantee  of  their  connection  and  of  the  possibility  of  their 
interaction.'1  This,  at  least,  is  obvious,  that  Schiller  is  main- 
taining that  such  action  is  metaphysically  possible,  and  the 
scientists  that  it  is  physically  impossible — opinions  by  no 
means  incompatible. 

Three  distinct  views  may  therefore  be  held  on  this 
subject  :■ 

i.  That  action  between  bodies  without  mass  contact  is 
both  metaphysically  and  physically  impossible.  This  appears 
to  have  been  the  view  of  Aristotle  and  S.  Thomas,  though  the 
latter,  at  any  rate,  does  not  seem  to  have  stated  it  explicitly. 
It  was  also  held  by  Suarez,2  and  is  still  maintained  by  modern 
Scholastics. 

2.  That  action  without  mass  contact  between  bodies  is 
physically  impossible,  but  that  its  metaphysical  impossi- 
bility has  not  been  proved.  This  is  the  view  put  forward 
by  Nys.3 

3.  That  such  action  is  both  physically  and  metaphysically 
possible. 

Those  who  hold  this  last  view,  further  maintain  that  such 
action  occurs  ;  and  it  is  an  opinion  which  has  found  favour 
both  with  great  scientists  such  as  Faraday,  as  well  as  with 
philosophers  as  Leibniz. 

That  mass  contact  between  bodies  is  a  metaphysically 

1  Schiller,  Riddles  of  the  Sphinx,  p.  66. 

2  Suarez,  Metaphysical  Disputations,  Disp.  18,  Sect.  8,  nn.  1  and  13. 

3  Nys,  Cosmologie,  Vol.  I,  Sect.  199. 


THE   QUALITY   OF  BODIES  113 

necessary  condition  of  action  appears  to  be  a  proposition 
incapable  of  proof  ;  nevertheless,  arguments  derived  from 
our  knowledge  of  natural  laws  seem  to  show  that  action  does 
not  take  place  between  two  bodies  without  such  contact  :  in 
other  words,  that,  as  far  as  our  knowledge  of  nature  at 
present  extends,  it  is  probably  true  to  say  that  mass  contact 
is  physically  necessary.  That  some  kind  of  contact  is 
absolutely  necessary  for  action  of  any  sort  between  two 
things  is  really  a  truism,  as  we  shall  see  ;  and  it  seems  to  be 
in  this  sense  that  the  axiom  '  action  at  a  distance  is  impos- 
sible '  should  be  understood. 

With  regard  to  the  physical  necessity,  there  are  some 
probable  arguments  which  show  that  the  laws  of  nature,  as 
at  present  known  to  us,  are  not  consistent  with  the  view 
that  action  between  bodies  can  take  place  without  mass 
contact. 

First,  we  may  argue  from  the  law  of  the  inverse  square, 
which  governs  the  actions  of  bodies  in  such  a  way  that  the 
intensity  of  the  action  varies  inversely  as  the  square  of  the 
distance  between  them,  and  so  diminishes  as  the  distance 
increases.  It  follows  that  they  cannot  act  on  one  another  at 
a  distance,  i.e.  without  mass  contact,  since  a  material  force 
can  only  be  diminished  by  a  material  resistance  which,  in  this 
hypothesis,  would  be  lacking,  since  the  bodies  would  be  sup- 
posed to  act  across  a  space  void  of  matter.  Since,  then, 
there  would  be  nothing  to  diminish  the  force  with  which 
they  act  on  one  another,  it  would  not  be  diminished  ;  unless 
we  are  ready  to  posit  an  effect  without  a  cause,  or  invoke 
spirits,  or  other  unknown  forces  to  account  for  the 
unaccountable. 

Secondly,  such  action  is  not  a  natural  mode  of  action,  since 
bodies  are  naturally  in  a  place,  and  just  as  the  being  of  a  body 
is  naturally  circumscribed  by  a  definite  place,  so  also  is  its 
action,  on  the  basis  of  the  general  principle  that  the  mode  of 
action  of  anything  corresponds  to  its  mode  of  being. 

As  against  this  opinion  the  following  objection  may  be 
urged.  Gravitation  is  propagated  instantaneously,  or,  at 
least,  with  a  velocity  which  has  been  estimated  to  be  at  least 
fifty  million  times  that  of  light  ;    all  bodies  appear  to  be 


ii4         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSPOHY 

absolutely  transparent  to  gravitational  action ;  and  it  is 
not  subject  to  any  kind  of  reflection  or  refraction.  It  seems 
also  to  be  independent  of  the  structure,  or  the  physical  and 
chemical  conditions  of  the  bodies  between  which  it  acts  :  its 
energy  is  unchangeable  and  inexhaustible.  Hence,  it  appears 
that  gravitation  acts  without  being  in  any  way  affected  by 
the  medium  through  which  it  may  appear  to  pass  ;  i.e.  that 
it  acts  at  a  distance. 

This  serious  difficulty  may  perhaps  be  met  on  the  lines  of 
the  classical  physics  by  supposing  that  gravitation  is  due  to 
waves  in  the  ether  of  space,  which,  by  hypothesis,  is  omni- 
present ;  waves  which  can  penetrate  intervening  matter 
even  more  easily  than  can  the  long  waves  of  wireless  tele- 
graphy.1 Another  solution,  however,  has  been  suggested  by 
the  theory  of  Einstein.  The  connecting  link  between  the 
two  is  to  be  found  in  a  sentence  written  by  Fitzgerald  in 
1894  :  '  Gravity  is  probably  due  to  a  change  in  the  structure 
of  the  ether,  produced  by  the  presence  of  matter.'2  In  the 
developed  theory  of  Einstein  there  are  in  space-time  natural 
paths,  along  which  bodies  move  naturally  ;  the  structure  of 
space-time  being  such  that  it  will  only  allow  of  certain 
definite  configurations.  Such  a  state  of  affairs  is  familiar  to 
us  in  bodies  with  which  we  are  constantly  dealing  in  every- 
day experience,  as  in  the  shapes  taken  by  liquids  in  motion, 
or  to  use  Eddington's  example,  in  a  piece  of  cloth  which  is 
gathered  into  puckers  ;  the  part  between  the  puckers  being 
capable  only  of  a  definite  configuration,  or,  conversely,  if  the 
part  between  the  puckers  is  to  lie  flat,  the  puckers  themselves 
must  be  of  a  particular  kind.3  Similarly,  in  this  view  space- 
time  allows  of  certain  curvatures  only,  and  since  these  curva- 
tures are  the  matter  in  it,  the  bodies  must  be  so  arranged  in  it 
that  they  will  not  create  any  unallowable  ones  ;  or,  it  would 
be  better  to  say  that  they  will  appear  to  arrange  themselves 
in  this  way.  Their  doing  so  is  their  falling  to  the  earth,  their 
passage  round  the  sun,  and  so  on,  So,  in  following  the  in- 
trinsic laws  of  space-time,  and  of  matter,  they  will  naturally 

1  Cf.  Lodge,  Ether  and  Reality,  pp.  44,  60,  and  Ch.  IV. 

2  Scientific  Writings,  p.  313. 

3  Eddington;  Nature  of  the  Physical  World,  pp.  127  f. 


THE  QUALITY  OF  BODIES  115 

move  in  certain  paths.  Just  as  in  Newtonian  physics  we 
imagine  bodies  to  move  naturally  along  straight  lines  in 
three-dimensional  space,  when  not  acted  on  by  any  forces, 
since  such  paths  will  be  the  shortest  distance  between  two 
points ;  so  in  the  curved  four-dimensional  continuum  of 
space-time,  the  bodies  will  still  tend  to  take  the  shortest 
track,  but  this  track  will  no  longer  be  a  straight  line,  but  a 
curve.  Hence,  the  earth  circling  round  the  sun,  the  stone 
falling  to  the  ground,  are  not,  according  to  this  view,  pulled 
out  of  their  natural  paths  by  some  force,  but  are  simply  fol- 
lowing that  path  in  space-time  which  is  the  shortest,  and 
does  not  entail  their  inducing  in  it  any  unallowable  curva- 
ture. So  gravitation  is  not  a  force  which  acts  between  bodies, 
but  the  appearance  of  pull  is  simply  due  to  the  fact  that  in 
the  regions  near  matter  space-time  is  curved,  and  the 
natural  paths  of  bodies  are  therefore  curved  also.  This  way 
of  regarding  gravitation,  therefore,  describes  it,  not  by  way 
of  cause  and  effect,  as  Newton  did,  but  simply  as  the  state- 
ment of  a  situation  :  space-time  being  of  a  particular  kind, 
and  only  amenable  to  certain  configurations,  bodies  move  in 
a  definite  fashion.  So  the  idea  of  gravitation  as  a  force  is 
got  rid  of,  and  with  it  the  objection  that  it  is  a  force  which 
acts  at  a  distance  ;  for  it  is  clear  that  if  there  is  no  gravita- 
tional action  between  bodies  at  all,  there  cannot  be  action  at 
a  distance  which  is  gravitational. 

To  turn  to  the  proposition  :  '  some  sort  of  presence  is 
required  for  action  between  things,'  it  can  hardly  be  denied 
that  we  are  justified  in  calling  it  a  truism.  For,  if  one  thing 
acts  on  another,  it  influences  it  in  some  way,  and  so  has  some 
connection  with  it,  or  is  not  altogether  separated  from  it. 
To  say  that  a  thing  can  act  at  a  distance  in  this  sense  is  an 
obvious  absurdity,  since  it  is  equivalent  to  saying  that  it  can 
influence  the  thing  on  which  it  acts,  while  it  remains  in  every 
way  separate  and  disconnected  from  it,  and  so  not  influencing 
it.  That,  if  there  is  not  mass  contact,  there  must  be  some 
medium  through  which  the  action  shall  pass  is  not,  and 
cannot  be,  proved  by  this  and  similar  arguments. 

So,  in  a  word,  we  may  say  that  there  seems  to  be  no  meta- 
physical   impossibility    involved    in    action    between    two 


n6         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

bodies  without  mass  contact,  but  that  physically  it  is  prob- 
able that  the  laws  of  nature  do  not  allow  of  it. 

For  the  whole  question,  see  Nys,  Cosmologie,  Vol.  I, 
pp.  256  ff.  Also  :  Hugon,  Cursus  Philosophies  Thomisticce , 
Vol.  VI,  pp.  142  ff. 

Note  :  The  explanation  given  above  of  Einstein's  account 
of  gravitation  is,  of  course,  entirely  inadequate.  All  that  is 
necessary  to  grasp  here  is  th?t,  according  to  Einstein,  gravi- 
tation is  not  regarded  as  a  pull  or  force,  and  so  cannot  be  an 
example  of  a  pull  which  acts  at  a  distance.  A  fuller  explana- 
tion is  given  by  Eddington  in  the  work  referred  to,  and  this 
is  probably  the  most  intelligible  account  of  a  non-technical 
kind.  (Eddington,  Nature  of  the  Physical  World,  Chaps.  VI 
and  VII.) 


CHAPTER  IX 

THE   MEASURE   OF  MOTION,   WHICH   IS   TIME 

Duration — Eternity,  Mvum,  and  Time — Division  of  Time — Non- 
Thomistic  Views  as  to  the  Nature  of  Time — Newton,  Kant, 
Leibniz,  Bergson. 

The  word  '  motion  '  no  doubt  means,  properly  speaking, 
successive  motion  for  which  time  is  required,  by  which 
motion  itself  is  measured  ;  and  so  the  consideration  of 
motion  naturally  leads  us  to  that  of  time.  The  whole  ques- 
tion as  to  the  nature  of  time  is  a  very  thorny  one,  for  as  soon 
as  we  begin  to  submit  it  to  analysis,  time,  which  seems  such 
an  obvious  fact  of  our  lives,  eludes  us,  and  has  '  softly  and 
silently  vanished  away.'  This  is  due  to  the  nature  of  our 
thought  which  can  only  deal  with  things  which  are  fixed  and 
permanent,  whereas  time  is  essentially  fluid  and  impermanent 
Nevertheless,  though  we  cannot  give  a  clear-cut  answer  to 
the  question — what  is  time  ? — and,  indeed,  such  an  answer 
would  be  its  own  refutation — we  can  discover  a  good  deal  as 
to  its  nature  by  careful  consideration. 

First,  then,  it  is  clear  that  time  is  a  species  of  duration  : 
and  to  say  a  thing  endures  is  to  say  that  it  continues  to 
exist,  so  that  duration  is  permanence  in  existence,  and  it 
might  be  thought  that  duration  is  either  to  be  identified  with 
the  thing  which  endures,  or,  if  not,  at  least  is  the  same  as  its 
existence.  Neither  of  these  opinions,  however,  is  tenable 
without  qualification,  for,  in  the  first  place,  the  hold  which 
anything  has  on  existence  is  not  something  which  belongs  to 
it  of  its  very  nature,  otherwise,  so  long  as  its  nature  was  not 
altered,  it  could  not  cease  to  exist,  which  is  contrary  to 
experience  ;  since  things  do  come  into  being  and  pass  away, 
which  they  could  not  do  if  existence  was  their  very  nature. 
It  is  clear  that  this  conclusion  would  not  be  conceded  by 

117 


n8         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

those,  such  as  Suarez,  who  identify  essence  and  existence  ; 
but,  even  if  this  be  done,  duration  is,  in  the  second  place, 
not  precisely  the  same  as  existence,  and  so,  as  the  nature  of 
the  thing,  for  to  say  that  a  thing  exists  durably  or  per- 
manently is  to  say  more  than  that  it  simply  exists. 

Whatever  differences  of  opinion  there  may  be  as  to  the 
relation  of  duration  to  the  enduring  thing,  the  Scholastics  all 
agree  in  distinguishing  three  kinds  of  duration  :  eternity, 
aevum  and  time  ;  the  first  being  the  duration  of  a  thing 
which  is  altogether  unchangeable,  the  second  that  of  a  thing 
which  is  subject  to  accidental  change,  though  it  remains 
immutable  in  its  substance,  the  third  the  duration  of  a 
thing  which  is  subject  both  to  substantial  and  to  accidental 
change. 

Eternity  is  defined  by  Boethius  as  '  interminabilis  vitce 
tota  simul  et  perfecta  possessio.'1  The  words  '  tota  simul '  ex- 
clude the  idea  of  succession,  and  the  word  '  perfecta  '  the 
idea  of  the  temporal  '  now,'  in  which  possession  of  life  and 
existence  is  imperfect,  since  it  is  essentially  transitory. 
Eternity  is,  strictly  speaking,  interminable,  since  it  has 
neither  beginning  nor  end.  Since  there  is  absolute  immuta- 
bility in  eternity,  it  is  clear  that  there  is  no  succession  in  an 
eternal  being,  nor  even  are  things  which  succeed  one  another 
successive  with  regard  to  it,  since,  having  no  beginning  or 
end,  it  includes  and  embraces  them  all.  '  Just  as,'  says  John 
of  S.  Thomas, '  if  there  were  a  tree  of  such  a  size  as  to  stretch 
out  over  all  the  waters  of  a  river,  it  would  coexist  with  all 
the  parts  of  the  river  together,  even  though  these  succeeded 
one  another.'2  Time,  on  the  other  hand,  is  intimately  con- 
nected with  succession,  of  which  we  get  our  first  notion  when 
we  notice  local  motion,  since  the  moving  thing  passes  through 
a  succession  of  places.  Now,  it  is  clear  that  such  movement 
takes  place  in  time,  and  at  first  sight  it  might  seem  that  time 
is  simply  the  motion  of  some  body.  So  the  day  seems  to  be 
the  revolution  of  the  earth  on  its  axis  ;  and  the  year  its 
passage  round  the  sun.  But  a  little  reflection  will  show  us 
that  though  time  and  motion  are  closely  connected,  yet  they 

1  Philosophies  Consolatio,  Lib.  V,  Ch.  VI,  io. 
*  Phil.  Nat.,  Q.  18,  A.  i,  diff.  3. 


TIME  119 

are  not  to  be  identified,  and  this  for  two  reasons  :  first, 
because  motion  is  something  which  belongs  to  the  thing 
which  is  moving,  whereas  time  affects  all  things  everywhere  ; 
and,  secondly,  because  motion  can  be  fast  or  slow,  but  time 
is  not.1  If  time  varied  with  the  movement,  as  it  would  have 
to  do  if  they  were  the  same,  we  could  never  say  of  anything 
that  it  moved  quickly  or  slowly  ;  and  the  fact  that  we  can 
do  so  shows  that  we  compare  the  motion  with  time,  for  we 
say  that  one  motion  is  quicker  than  another,  if  it  takes  a 
shorter  time  to  traverse  the  same  distance.  Hence  motion  is 
measured  by  time. 

Again,  though  time  implies  succession,  this  latter  is  not 
the  same  as  time,  since  some  successions  are  non-temporal, 
e.g.  the  succession  in  the  series  of  ordinal  numbers.  Never- 
theless, since  time  implies  succession,  we  shall  have  to  state 
its  successive  character  in  our  definition  of  it.  All  these 
elements  were  included  in  the  Aristotelean  definition  of  time, 
which  was  adopted  by  S.  Thomas,  and  is  now  generally 
accepted  by  Scholastics,  viz. :  Time  is  the  number  of  move- 
ment in  respect  of  before  and  after,    tovto  ydp  eo-nv  6  xp°voi>< 

api9p.hs  KivTjcrecos   KaTa  to  Tporepov  kou  vo-repov.2 

The  word  d/nfyxos  here  (i.e.  number)  is  equivalent  to 
measure,  for  all  quantity  is  measurable,  and  measure  is 
expressed  by  number.  Time  is  the  measure  of  movement 
only,  that  which  is  immobile  is  not  in  time  ;  and,  further,  by 
this  phrase  we  affirm  that  time  is  not  the  same  as  movement, 
since  it  is  its  measure. 

Lastly,  the  words  '  in  respect  of  before  and  after  '  indicate 
that  time  does  not  apply  to  movement  precisely  as  move- 
ment, but  in  so  far  as  it  is  successive.  Hence  the  words  do 
not  merely  repeat  the  notion  of  time  which  they  are  intended 
to  explain,  as  Plotinus  thought,3  but  indicate  expressly  its 
successive  character. 

In  this  definition,  as  indeed  in  our  everyday  conceptions, 
time  is  thought  of  as  a  unity  ;  but  it  is  difficult  to  see  on 
what  such  a  unity  can  be  founded,  for  the  motions  of  which 
it  is  the  measure  are  multiple.     The  Aristotelean  physics 

1  Cf.  Aristotle,  Physics,  2i8bg.  2  Aristotle,  Physics,  2igbi. 

8  Inge,  The  Philosophy  of  Plotinus,  Vol.  I,  p.  171. 


120         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

gave,  at  least,  a  partial  answer  to  this  question,  since  Aris- 
totle regarded  motion  in  a  circle  as  the  primary  kind  of  local 
movement,  and  thought  that  the  celestial  sphere  moved 
uniformly.  Hence,  in  his  view,  there  is  one  uniform  motion 
which  dominates  all  others,  and  so  one  from  which  the  unity 
of  time  can  be  derived. *  It  is  from  this  notion  that  we  derive 
our  way  of  speaking  of  time,  and  the  changes  of  human  affairs, 
as  cyclical.  It  is,  however,  clear  to  us  at  the  present  day,  that 
there  is  in  nature  no  known  movement  which  is  absolutely 
uniform,  and  consequently  none  which  can  be  taken  to 
standardise  and  unify  time.  Nevertheless,  such  a  movement 
can  be  readily  conceived  of,  and  was,  in  fact,  used  in  New- 
tonian physics,  under  the  name  of  mathematical  time.  It  is 
evidently  a  mental  fiction. 

If,  then,  we  must  abandon  the  hope  of  finding  any  absolute 
time,  we  nevertheless  are  well  acquainted  with  relative  times, 
and  so  can  continue,  with  regard  to  the  things  whose  motion 
is  measured  by  them,  to  speak  of  them  as  being  in  time. 

What,  then,  are  these  things  which  are  in  time  ? 

As  Aristotle  points  out,  '  to  be  in  time,'  may  have  three 
senses  :  (i)  to  be  when  time  is,  (2)  to  be  a  part  or  attribute  of 
time,  and  (3)  to  be  measurable  by  time.2  The  first  of  these 
senses  can  obviously  be  ruled  out  at  once,  it  is  simply  an 
ambiguity  of  expression.  Of  the  other  two  senses  the  second 
applies  to  past,  present,  and  future,  which  are,  in  a  wide 
sense,  parts  of  time  ;  the  third  to  events  which  are  measur- 
able by  time  ;  i.e.  all  things  whose  being  is  mutable  or  sub- 
ject to  change. 

The  Division  of  Time. 

There  are  two  kinds  of  time  :  imaginary  and  real,  the  first 
being  external  to  the  material  universe,  and  containing 
within  itself  all  durations.  The  second  is  the  measure  of  real 
motion.  We  have  seen  that  this  absolute  imaginary  time  is  a 
mere  mental  fiction,  and  we  shall  shortly  see  what  is  to  be 
said  as  to  the  extra-mental  existence  of  '  real  time.'    This 

1  Aristotle,  Physics,  223^12-22 4a2  ;  cf.  S.  Thomas,  loc.  cit.,  and  in 
IV  Phys.,  Lect.  17,  No.  4. 

2  Aristotle,  Physics,  22137  sqq.  ;  S.  Thomas  in  IV  Phys.,  Lect.  15,  No.  3. 


TIME  121 

last  is  of  two  kinds  :  time  as  duration,  and  time  as  a  measure. 
The  first  is  also  called  intrinsic,  and  the  second  extrinsic, 
time.  Extrinsic  time  is  also  of  two  kinds  :  primary  and 
secondary.  Primary  time  is  the  measure  of  the  motion  of 
the  earth,  secondary  being  the  measure  of  any  particular 
motion,  such  as  that  of  a  clock,  or  clock-time.  Primary  time 
is  again  divided  into  sidereal,  apparent,  and  mean  time.  The 
sidereal  day  is  the  interval  between  two  consecutive  south- 
ings of  a  particular  star.  Apparent  time  is  derived  from  the 
motion  of  the  sun,  the  solar  day  being  defined  as  the  interval 
between  two  consecutive  southings  of  the  sun.  This  interval 
is  by  no  means  constant,  owing  to  the  inclination  of  the 
ecliptic  to  the  equator,  and  the  lack  of  uniformity  in  the 
velocity  of  the  sun.  The  mean  time  is  the  average  of 
the  apparent  time,  the  maximum  divergence  being  about 
sixteen  minutes. 

We  are  now  faced  with  the  difficult  question  of  the  extra 
mental  status  of  time.  Aristotle  raised  the  question  whether 
there  would  be  time  if  there  were  not  soul  (mind),  but  gave 
no  definite  answer  to  it.1  We  have  to  enquire  as  to  the 
objectivity  both  of  time  as  a  duration — which  is  the  con- 
tinued existence  of  motion — and  of  time  as  a  measure,  whose 
definition  is  the  number  of  movement  in  respect  of  before 
and  after.  At  first  sight  it  appears  as  if  time  as  a  duration 
were  something  which  exists  quite  apart  from  the  mind,  but 
a  little  reflection  shows  that  all  that  can  be  said  to  exist  in 
this  way  is  the  moving  thing  and  its  successive  states  ;  the 
continued  existence  of  motion  not  being  found  in  nature. 
For  it  is  clear  that  a  car  running  along  a  road,  though  its 
motion  is  continuous,  is  yet  to  be  found  in  reality  at  only 
one  potential  point  of  its  course  at  any  one  (potential) 
moment ;  whereas  to  have  continued  or  enduring  existence 
it  would  either  have  to  be  fixed  at  one  point,  not  passing 
through  a  potential  point,  or  stretching  out  from  one  point 
to  another,  in  which  case  it  would  be  in  two  places  at  once. 
There  is  a  striking  passage  in  S.  Thomas'  commentary  on 
the  Physics,  which  deserves  to  be  quoted.2  He  says  :  '  The 
notion  '  (the  word  used  is  '  ratio,'  which  means  both  nature 

1  Aristotle,  Physics,  223321-29.  2  In  III  Phys.,  Lect.  5,  No.  17. 


122         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

and  notion)  '  of  movement  is  made  complete,  not  only  by 
what  there  is  of  motion  in  nature,  but  also  by  what  the  mind 
apprehends.  For,  of  motion,  nothing  more  exists  in  nature 
than  an  imperfect  act,  which  is  a  kind  of  beginning,  in  the 
thing  which  is  moved,  of  a  perfect  act.  Thus,  in  a  thing 
which  is  turning  white,  there  is  already  some  whiteness.  In 
order,  however,  that  such  imperfect  act  should  have  the 
nature  of  movement,  it  is  further  required  that  we  should 
conceive  it  as  a  mean  between  two  extremes,  of  which  the 
preceding  one  bears  to  it  the  relation  of  potency  to  act,  and 
the  one  which  follows  it  that  of  act  to  potency  :  which  is  the 
reason  that  we  call  motion  the  act  of  that  which  is  in  potency.' 
Thus  the  duration  of  motion  is  not  a  reality  found  in 
nature  apart  from  the  mind.  It  is  our  mind,  which  is  endowed 
with  memory,  which  gives  unity  and  so  being  to  motion,  and 
to  the  duration  of  motion,  as  a  whole.  Further,  its  duration 
is  the  foundation  of  time  as  a  measure,  since  only  in  so  far 
as  it  is  an  enduring  whole  does  it  lend  itself  to  measurement. 
This  conclusion  is  strengthened  by  considering  the  attempts 
that  have  been  made  to  account  for  the  existence  of  time  : 
for  some,  as  Suarez,  have  maintained  that  time  exists  by 
reason  of  its  parts,  the  past  and  future,  which  continually 
flow  on.  It  is,  however,  difficult  to  see  how  a  thing  can  exist 
by  reason  of  parts  which  do  not  exist  themselves  ;  for  the 
past  is  already  dead,  and  the  future  is  not  yet  born.  Con- 
sequently, S.  Thomas  and  his  school  affirm  that  in  so  far  as 
time  exists,  it  does  so  by  reason  of  the  present  instant, 
which  is  not  a  part  of  time,  but  the  indivisible  link  of  its 
parts,  the  past  and  future.  This  instant  must  exist  since  it 
is  the  measure  of  unity  of  a  definite  state  of  the  moving 
thing,  and  without  such  definite  state  the  moving  thing  itself 
could  not  exist.  It  is,  however,  present  only  in  so  far  as  it  is 
considered  by  the  mind  in  relation  to  the  past  and  future  ; 
and  it  is  clear  that  it  cannot  make  the  past  and  future  exist, 
since  the  past  cannot  exist  in  the  present,  and  to  speak  of  the 
present  presupposes  that  the  future  is  not  yet  existing.  So 
we  are  brought  back  to  our  former  conclusion  that  neither 
time  as  a  duration,  nor  time  as  a  measure,  exist,  or  are  real, 
apart  from  the  mind.    This,  however,  should  not  blind  us  to 


TIME  123 

the  fact  that  there  is  an  element  of  time  which  has  such  extra- 
mental  existence,  viz.  the  indivisible  of  time,  the  instant. 
So  S.  Thomas  says  :  '  If  motion  had  some  fixed  existence  in 
things,  as  a  stone  or  a  horse  have,  it  would  be  possible  to 
say  absolutely  that  just  as,  even  if  the  soul  does  not  exist, 
there  exists  a  number  of  stones,  so,  even  if  the  soul  does  not 
exist,  there  would  be  a  number  of  motion  which  is  time.  But 
motion  has  no  fixed  existence  in  things,  and  in  things  there 
is  found  nothing  actual  of  motion,  except  a  certain  indivisible 
of  motion,  which  is  the  division  of  motion  :  but  the  totality 
of  motion  is  comprehended  through  the  consideration  of  the 
soul  which  compares  the  former  to  the  latter  disposition  of 
the  moving  thing.  So,  therefore,  time  also  has  no  existence 
outside  the  soul,  except  with  regard  to  its  indivisible,  but 
the  very  totality  of  time  is  comprehended  through  the  order- 
ing of  the  soul  which  enumerates  before  and  after  in  motion.'1 
So,  he  adds,  time  has  an  imperfect  existence  only,  apart  from 
the  mind,  just  as  motion  itself  has. 

Taken  then  as  a  whole  duration  or  measure,  it  exists  in  the 
mind  only.2  In  this  delicate  doctrine  as  to  the  existence  of 
time,  it  is  essential  not  to  overlook  either  the  objective  or 
subjective  element  in  it :  both  of  which  must  be  preserved 
in  their  proper  proportions.  Those  who  dissent  from  the 
Thomist  view  do  so,  in  fact,  because  they  ascribe  undue 
weight  to  one  or  other  of  these  elements,  and  so  fall  into  two 
classes  which  may,  for  convenience,  be  called  Ultra-Realist 
and  Subjectivist. 

Non-Thomistic  Views  of  the  Nature  of  Time. 

Though  it  does  not  come  within  the  scope  of  this  explana- 
tion to  set  out  extraneous  opinions  for  their  own  sake,  yet,  in 
this  case,  a  short  review  of  the  principal  ones  will  serve  to 
clarify  the  meaning,  and  emphasise  the  balance  and  sanity 
of  the  Thomist  view. 

I.  The  Ultra-Realist  view  is  represented  in  the  first  place 
by  Gassendi,  who,  basing  his  theories  on  those  of  Epicurus, 
considered  time  to  be  something  which  is  neither  substance 

1  In  IV  Phys.,  Lect.  23,  No.  5. 

*  Cf.  Nys,  La  Notion  du  Temps,  pp.  59  f.,  No.  38. 


124         MODERN   THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

nor  accident,  and  which  is  eternal  and  uncreated.  Newton 
and  Clarke,  in  a  somewhat  similar  way,  held  that  time  is  a 
divine  attribute.  Gassendi,  however,  as  a  theist,  was  in  an 
impossible  position,  since  there  cannot  be  two  uncreated  and 
eternal  beings  ;  and  the  Newtonian  view  is  faced  with  the 
difficulty  that  the  divine  attributes  are  immutable,  and  there 
is  no  succession  in  them,  whereas  time  is  essentially  successive. 
The  elaborate  theory  of  space-time  put  forward  recently  by 
Professor  Alexander  seems  to  have  affinities  with  these  views. 
He  considers  it  to  be  the  fundamental  stuff  of  the  universe 
from  which  Deity  is  progressively  emerging.  It  seems  diffi- 
cult to  regard  this  view  as  other  than  pantheistic,  though  its 
author  has  repudiated  this  interpretation  of  it. 

II.     The  Subjectivist  Views. 

1.  Kant  regarded  time  as  an  a  priori  intuition  of  the  sensi- 
bility, something,  that  is,  which  belongs  to  the  very  texture 
of  our  senses  :  so  that,  for  him,  it  is  purely  subjective.  This 
is  evidently  false  if  we  recognise  motion  as  a  real  foundation 
of  time  ;  and  moreover  it  is  contrary  to  experience,  since,  in 
observing  some  extended  sensible  object,  such  as  a  landscape, 
our  observations  are  successive,  while  the  landscape  appears 
as  a  static  whole.  If,  however,  succession  were  something 
which  directly  affected  our  sensibility  alone,  both  it  and  its 
objects  ought  to  be  affected  by  it,  or  neither  of  them  ;  so 
that,  on  Kant's  hypothesis,  it  should  be  impossible  for  us  to 
have  a  successive  knowledge  of  a  simultaneous  whole.1 

2.  Leibniz  at  least  inclines  to  over-emphasise  the  subjec- 
tive character  of  time  :  for  he  defines  it  as  the  '  order  of 
successions/2  He  remarks  that  a  thing  of  which  no  part 
ever  exists  cannot  exist  ;  and  in  the  case  of  time,  nothing 
exists  except  the  present  instant,  which  is  not  a  part  of  time  ; 
and  concludes  that  time  cannot  be  other  than  an  ideal  being. 
It  will  be  seen  that  this  view  has  close  affinity  with  that  of 
S.  Thomas  ;  for  they  are  at  one  in  recognising  the  purely 
mental  character  of  absolute  time,  and  also  that  the  only 
element   of  time  which  exists  in   nature   is  the  instant. 

1  Cf.  Nys,  op.  cit.,  p.  226,  No.  138. 

s  Cf.  3rd  letter  to  Clarke  and  5th  letter  to  Clarke  (on  Par.  10). 


TIME  125 

S.  Thomas,  however,  notices  what  Leibniz  overlooks,  that  this 
instant  is  the  number  of  the  motion  of  the  body,  and  corres- 
ponds to  the  indivisible  of  motion,  which,  though  the  only 
actuality  in  motion,  is  at  the  same  time  potential  to  the 
further  process  of  motion,  so  that  time  exists  as  a  perfect  and 
actual  being  ideally  only,  but  as  an  imperfect  and  potential 
one  in  things.  It  seems,  therefore,  not  unjust  to  Leibniz  to 
say  that  his  teaching  on  this  point  is  not  so  well  balanced  as 
that  of  S.  Thomas,  and  that  his  theory  is  of  the  subjectivist 
type,  though  not  of  so  extreme  a  kind  as  that  of  Kant. 
Further,  in  his  definition  and  view  of  time,  Leibniz  loses 
sight  of  its  essential  continuity  ;  for  the  definition  does  not 
take  account  of  the  fact  that  time  requires  continuous 
motion,  as  well  as  the  permanence  of  the  thing  which  moves. 
Order  does  not  necessarily  imply  either  of  these,  for  there 
can  be  order  among  discontinuous  things,  and,  consequently, 
apart  from  the  permanence  of  the  thing  which  is  subject  to 
order.  Hence,  Leibniz's  definition  does  not  discriminate 
between  that  by  which  the  motion  of  material  things  is 
measured,  and  that  which  applies  to  the  motion  of  pure 
spirits  :  which  latter  is  discrete,  not  continuous. 

Lastly,  to  define  time  as  the  order  of  successions  is  a  loose 
way  of  speaking,  for  order  is  a  consequence  of  succession,  and 
so  of  time,  rather  than  constitutive  of  successive  duration, 
or  time.  There  is  order  in  the  succession  of  things  because 
of  the  motion  by  which  the  things  succeed  one  another,  not 
conversely  :  for  it  is  not  true  to  say  that  there  is  motion 
because  there  is  order. 

III.     Bergson's  Theory  of  Time. 

According  to  Bergson,  there  are  two  kinds  of  time,  homo- 
geneous and  heterogeneous.  The  latter  is  the  time  of  our 
experience,  and  is  named  by  him  '  la  durie,'  to  which  no 
English  expression  exactly  corresponds.  Homogeneous 
time,  which  is  what  we  ordinarily  mean  when  we  use  the 
word  time,  is,  in  his  view,  merely  space,  on  to  which  the  mind 
projects  psychological  time,  the  succession  of  our  conscio1- ' 
states,  thus  making  it  appear  to  be  a  successive  and  con- 
tinuous reality.    In  fact,  it  is  nothing  but  an  illusion  for  there 


126  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

is  no  true  succession  in  things  which  are  said  to  be  measured 
by  time,  since  one  state  has  entirely  disappeared  when 
another  appears.  So  he  writes  :  '  Doubtless  exterior  things 
change,  but  their  moments  only  succeed  one  another  with 
respect  to  a  consciousness  which  remembers  them.  We 
observe  outside  us,  at  any  given  moment,  a  collection  of 
simultaneous  positions ;  nothing  remains  of  the  former 
simultaneities.'1 

Hence,  the  only  time  which  is  not  illusory,  and  which  he 
regards  as  real,  is  the  heterogeneous  time,  or  succession, 
which  accompanies  the  development  of  our  conscious  states. 
Such  development  is  purely  qualitative,  and  its  parts  can  only 
be  qualitatively,  never  quantitatively,  distinguished,  so  that 
they  are  absolutely  heterogeneous  ;  for  it  is  clear  that  all 
our  psychic  acts  are  unextended — it  is  impossible  to  have  a 
yard  of  thought — and  so  if  distinct  their  distinction  can  be 
qualitative  only. 

There  can  be  no  question  as  to  the  subjective  character  of 
this  theory  ;  and  to  make  of  time  an  affection  of  our  con- 
scious states  is  to  contradict  completely  the  common-sense 
notion  of  it,  which  undoubtedly  attaches  it  to  bodies.  What 
is  more,  it  is  only  the  permanent  which  changes,  and  the 
permanent  endures  :  so  that  it  is  inconsistent  to  admit  that 
things  change  and  to  deny  their  duration.  Moreover,  if  time 
attaches  only  to  our  conscious  states,  each  one  of  us  will  live 
in  his  own  time,  and  there  will  be  no  unique  sense  in  which 
two  events  can  be  said  to  be  simultaneous.  This,  however, 
is  to  deny  time,  not  to  explain  it,  for  the  notion  of  time 
surely  implies,  at  least,  the  possibility  of  comparing  the 
position  of  two  events  in  the  world  process.  Without  this 
capacity,  it  is  altogether  useless.  Of  the  characteristics  of 
time,  as  all  men  conceive  it,  viz.  as  measuring  events,  as 
having  parts,  past,  present,  and  future,  and  as  continuous, 
the  only  one  which  is,  in  the  end,  retained  by  this  theory  is 
the  last,  and  that  illegitimately  ;  for  Bergsonian  time  is,  in 
fact,  the  series  of  irreducible  different  qualities,  which,  there- 
fore, can  never  form  a  unity  or  continuity.  Much  more 
might  be  added  in  criticism  of  the  theory,  but  these  remarks 

1  Essai  sur  les  donnes  de  la  conscience,  p.  173. 


TIME  127 

may  suffice  to  show  that  it  is  irreconcilable  with  common 
sense,  and  inconsistent  in  itself  ;  though  highly  ingenious, 
and  devised  with  the  best  of  intentions,  viz.  to  rescue  living 
things,  and  especially  conscious  processes  from  the  grip  of  a 
deterministic  mechanism. 

(For  a  fuller  discussion,  see  Nys,  La  Notion  du  Temps.) 

Note.  The  theory  of  Einstein  with  respect  to  the  relativity 
of  space  and  time  is  well  known  :  but  it  would  be  to  go  beyond 
the  limits  of  a  simple  explanation  of  Scholastic  philosophy 
to  attempt  to  explain  and  comment  on  it  here.  The  reader 
may  be  referred  to  Einstein's  own  explanation  of  it  in  his 
book,  The  Theory  of  Relativity  (Methuen)  ;  and  there  are 
many  other  explanations  of  it  in  English,  such  as  those 
given  by  Professor  Eddington  in  various  works,  e.g.  The 
Nature  of  the  Physical  World.  Scholastic  comments  on  it 
can  be  found  in  Nys'  monographs  on  Space  and  Time,  cited 
above  ;  and  a  good  discussion  of  it  from  a  metaphysical 
point  of  view  is  contained  in  Maritain's  Reflexions  sur 
V intelligence.  The  Prcelectiones  Cosmologice,  by  Fr.  Dario, 
S.J.  (Paris  :  Beauchesne)  can  also  be  consulted. 


CHAPTER  X 

SUBSTANTIAL   CHANGE   IN   GENERAL 

Meaning    of    Substantial    Change — The    Plurality   of    Forms — The 
Source  of  the  New  Substantial  Form  in  Generation. 

In  considering  the  quality  of  the  material  world  (mobile 
being),  which  is  motion,  we  have  seen  what  is  meant  by 
motion  in  general,  and  how  material  beings  are  affected 
extrinsically  by  their  motion  through  space.  We  now  turn 
to  that  motion,  or  change,  which  is  intrinsic  to  them.  Such 
change  is  of  two  kinds  :  substantial,  by  which  their  very 
nature  is  changed,  and  accidental,  by  which  their  qualities 
are  altered.  There  are  two  questions  which  require  separate 
treatment  with  regard  to  substantial  change,  that  of  sub- 
stantial change  in  general,  and  that  of  the  particular  kind  of 
substantial  change  which  occurs  when  two  or  more  simple 
elements  combine  to  form  a  chemical  compound. 

With  regard  to  substantial  change  in  general,  we  notice 
that  the  changing  of  one  substance  into  another  involves 
both  the  appearance  of  a  new  substance,  and  the  disappear- 
ance of  the  old.  It  is  therefore  called  by  Aristotle  generation 
(yfveo-is)  and  corruption  (<f>dopa). 

Generation  is  defined  as  the  change  by  means  of  which 
some  real  subject,  which  before  the  change  did  not  have 
existence,  receives  it ;  while  corruption  is  the  change  by 
means  of  which  some  real  subject,  which  before  the  change 
had  existence,  loses  it.  The  real  subject  referred  to  in  both 
cases  is  the  compound  of  matter  and  form.  So,  for  example, 
assuming  for  the  moment  that  wood  and  the  carbon  which 
results  from  burning  it  are  substances  of  different  natures, 
we  have  the  carbon  receiving  existence,  which  it  did  not 
have  before,  and  the  wood  losing  that  which  it  had.  The 
coming-into-being  of  the  carbon  is  the  passing-out-of-being 

128 


SUBSTANTIAL  CHANGE   IN   GENERAL       129 

of  the  wood,  so  that  the  Scholastics  say  that  the  generation 
of  one  thing  is  the  corruption  of  another.  Thus,  that  which 
is  produced  by  generation  is  the  concrete  thing,  in  our 
example,  the  carbon.  This  carbon  is,  moreover,  a  certain 
nature  which  exists,  and  one  which  comes  into  being  as  a 
result  of  generation  ;  so  that  it  is  clear  that  the  nature  of 
carbon  is  itself  a  product  of  generation  ;  not,  however,  as 
that  which  is  directly  generated  in  itself,  but  as  a  constituent 
of  the  concrete  thing.  So  the  Scholastics  call  it  the  '  terminus 
qui  generationis  '  as  contrasted  with  the  '  terminus  quod,' 
the  thing  which  is  generated.  The  nature  itself  is  made  of  a 
definite  and  specific  kind  by  the  substantial  form,  which  is 
therefore  also  a  terminus  qui  of  generation.  It  is  clear, 
further,  that  there  is  no  moment  of  time  between  the  dis- 
appearance of  one  nature,  one  form,  and  the  coming  of 
another,  since  the  disappearance  of  one  is  the  appearance  of 
the  other.  Nevertheless,  in  substantial  change  the  first  form 
does  disappear  entirely,  according  to  the  teaching  of  S. 
Thomas  ;  so  that,  in  his  view,  matter  is  stripped  of  all 
substantial  form  in  this  process.  The  truth  of  this  opinion 
has  been,  and  still  is,  hotly  contested  ;  and  we  must  pause 
to  consider  it  more  fully. 

Question  I.     On  the  Plurality  of  Forms. 

Whether  we  admit  S.  Thomas'  view  or  not  will  depend 
on  whether  we  allow  a  plurality  of  forms  in  one  being.  Until 
the  time  of  S*.  Thomas  the  possibility  of  there  being  many 
substantial  forms  in  a  thing,  which  still  remained  essentially 
one,  and  indeed  that  there  actually  were  many  such  forms, 
was  generally  admitted  by  Scholastics.  S.  Thomas,  however, 
always  held  firmly  to  the  opposite  opinion,1  being,  as  Pro- 
fessor Taylor  says,  '  too  sound  an  Aristotelean  '  to  admit 
such  plurality.2  The  views  of  his  opponents  on  this  question, 
and  so  on  the  process  of  substantial  change,  were  of  two 
kinds,  of  which  the  first  is  that  some  substantial  form  does 
remain  throughout  the  change.  So  Avicebron  (Ibn  Gebirol) , 
according  to  S.  Thomas,3  held  that  in  a  man  there  would  be  a 

1  But  cf.  Fr.  Roland-Gosselin's  edition  of  De  Ente  et  Essentia,  pp.  no  ff. 

2  Platonism  and  its  Influence,  p.  127. 
8  De  Spiritualibus  Creaturis,  Art.  3. 


130         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

hierarchy  of  forms,  beginning  with  the  form  of  substance,  to 
which  is  added  that  of  corporeality,  then  of  vegetative  life, 
then  of  sensitive  life,  and  finally  of  intellectual  life.  Scotus 
admitted  a  form  of  corporeality  in  living  things,  and  taught 
that  it  remains  on  the  departure  of  the  soul  ;x  while  Albert 
the  Great  held  that  the  forms  of  the  elements  remain  in  a  mix- 
ture, subsumed  under  the  form  of  the  mixture,  which  is 
new ;  as  the  Greeks  in  the  Trojan  horse  were  subsumed 
under  the  form  of  horse,  though  they  did  not  lose  their  own 
forms,  if  we  may  use  a  very  inadequate  example.  A  similar 
view  was  held  by  Avicenna  and  Averroes. 

The  second  way  of  regarding  this  process  of  change  is  that 
of  Suarez,  who,  though  allowing  that  no  substantial  form 
remains  throughout  the  change,  yet,  since  he  holds  that 
accidents  are  individuals  of  themselves,  not  by  reason  of  the 
substances  in  which  they  inhere,2  is  able  to  grant  that  the 
accidents  of  the  generated  thing  are  the  same  individual 
ones  as  those  which  were  found  in  the  corrupted  thing.  Apart 
from  this,  his  opinion  is  practically  the  same  as  that  of 
S.  Thomas.  Those  who  differ  from  S.  Thomas  maintain 
that  his  position  is  unintelligible,  for  they  say  that  if  there 
be  no  form  remaining,  we  shall  have  absolute  indetermina- 
tion,  which  is  the  same  as  nothing.  This  is,  in  fact,  the  denial 
of  the  reality  of  pure  potency  :  and  as  we  have  already  seen 
neither  Scotus  nor  Suarez  is  willing  to  admit  that  matter  is 
pure  potency  without  any  act  (cf.,  p.  48).  Further,  they 
object  that  when  one  form  disappears  there  will  be  a  moment, 
if  not  in  time,  at  least  in  the  order  of  intelligibility,  when  the 
subject  of  the  first  form,  lacking  that  form,  will  vanish  ; 
since  the  Thomists  admit  that  matter  cannot  exist  without 
form.  Hence,  in  order  that  we  may  have  a  common  subject, 
it  must  be  furnished  with  a  form  independent  of  those  which 
it  loses  or  acquires  in  the  change.  Apart  from  these  theor- 
etical objections,  it  has  recently  been  urged  by  Fr.  Descoqs,3 
and  others,  that  the  facts  show  that  the  subject  of  change  is 
not  first,  but  second,  matter. 

1  In  IV  Sent.  dist.  XI,  Q.  3,  A.  2. 

2  Disputationes  Metaphysiccz,  Disp.  V. 

8  Essai  Critique  sur  I'HyUmorphisme,  pp.  31  fl. 


SUBSTANTIAL  CHANGE  IN  GENERAL       131 

The  Thomists  reply  that  they  are  compelled  to  adhere  to 
their  doctrine  that  at  the  moment  of  change  no  substantial 
or  accidental  form  remains  by  irresistible  metaphysical 
arguments.  With  regard  to  substantial  form,  it  is  evident 
that  if  it  be  true  that  there  can  be  only  one  substantial  form 
in  one  compound,  since  change  of  substance  or  nature  must 
mean  that  the  old  nature  passes  away  and  a  new  one  takes 
its  place,  and  substantial  form  is  that  which  makes  a  thing 
to  be  of  a  definite  kind  substantially,  this  too  will  pass  away 
at  the  moment  of  change,  and  if  it  is  the  only  one,  none  will 
be  left.  The  question,  therefore,  resolves  itself  into  that 
concerning  the  plurality  of  substantial  forms  in  a  body 
which  is  an  essential  unity  ;  as  we  have  already  stated. 
Though  we  mentioned  shortly,  at  an  earlier  stage  (vid.  p.  50), 
the  reasons  which  S.  Thomas  gives  for  excluding  a  plurality 
of  forms,  as  a  corollary  to  our  discussion  of  the  potentiality 
of  matter,  it  is  necessary  to  examine  the  question  rather 
more  fully  here,  as  it  is  one  of  the  main  arches  of  the  Thomist 
structure,  and  is  a  characteristic  architectural  feature  of  it. 

There  are  two  questions  to  be  asked  :  first,  What  do  we 
mean  by  the  phrase  :  '  a  being  which  is  essentially  one  '  ? 
and,  second,  Are  there  any  such  beings  ? 

Can  we  say,  in  answer  to  the  first  question,  that  we  mean 
a  being  whose  nature  is  itself  a  compound  of  several,  so 
that  E,  its  nature,  is  compounded  of  E1}  E2,  E3,  .  .  .  etc.  ? 
This  is  surely  impossible,  for  the  thing  will  have  these 
natures  Ex,  etc.,  either  all  at  once  or  in  succession.  If  it  has 
them  all  at  once,  it  clearly  has  a  number  of  natures,  since, 
by  hypothesis,  they  are  different,  and  therefore  cannot  have 
a  single  nature.  If  it  has  them  successively,  when  it  has 
nature  E2,  it  will  already  be  a  definite  and  determinate  kind 
of  being  ;  and  so  cannot  be  made  a  definite  being  by  having 
a  nature  E2  added  to  it.  For,  just  as  it  is  true  to  say  that 
nothing  gives  what  it  has  not  already  got,  so  also  is  it  true 
that  nothing  gets  or  receives  what  it  has  already.  This  is 
true  even  in  the  accidental  order,  as  for  example,  it  is  imposs- 
ible to  make  a  man  a  millionaire  if  he  already  is  one  ;  and  it 
is  certainly  true  in  the  substantial,  a  man  cannot  be  made  a 
man,  a  determinate  nature  cannot  be  made  a  determinate 


132         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

nature.  To  doubt  this  would  indeed  be  to  doubt  the  prin- 
ciple of  identity — being  is  being — from  which  follows  the 
principle  of  Parmenides  :  '  from  being,  being  cannot  come 
to  be,  since  it  already  is,'  which,  with  the  precision  imported 
into  it  by  Aristotle,  becomes  :  '  from  being  in  act,  being  in 
act  cannot  come  to  be.'  And  this  is  precisely  the  case  in 
point,  since  being  which  has  an  essence  is  an  actual  being, 
and  so  by  the  addition  of  another  essence  cannot  become 
one.  It  is  already  constituted  as  a  substantial  nature,  so 
that  any  addition  to  it  can  only  modify  that  nature,  not 
constitute  it.  So  S.  Thomas  says  :  '  Quod  advenit  alicui  post 
esse  completum,  advenit  ei  accidentaliter .'  (Contra  Gentiles, 
Lib.  II,  c.  58.)  So  it  is  clear  that  by  essential  unity  we  must 
mean  that  the  thing  which  has  it,  has  one  nature  only,  for  no 
kind  of  compound  of  natures  will  satisfy  the  conditions. 
But  it  might  be  said  :  '  No  doubt  in  the  abstract  essential 
unity  means  that  there  is  a  single  nature,  but  in  the  concrete 
existing  thing  is  it  not  possible  that  several  natures  should  so 
fit  in  with  one  another  that  all  should  be  united  in  the  bond 
of  a  single  existence,  thus  giving  us  a  substantial  unity  ;  in 
other  words,  that  though  there  may  be  several  substantial 
forms  in  a  body,  yet  it  may  exist  as  a  unity  ?  '  If  we  con- 
sider this  we  see  that  it  is  impossible  to  agree  with  this  sug- 
gestion, for  substantial  form  is  that  which,  when  it  is  joined 
to  matter,  makes  a  compound  which  is  capable  of  receiving 
existence,  neither  form  nor  matter  being  capable  of  doing 
so  in  separation,  since  they  are  only  principles  of  being.  If, 
then,  the  compound  receives  existence — as  it  must  do  in 
order  to  be  a  concrete  thing — the  existence  which  it  receives 
will  be  existence  without  any  qualification  or  addition, 
making  it  pass  from  the  realm  of  mere  possibilities  to  that  of 
actual  existing  things,  for  if  it  does  not  do  this  the  thing  will 
not  pass  out  of  the  abstract  order.  If,  however,  it  does  do  it, 
any  further  existence  cannot  do  it,  since  it  is  already  done, 
and  so  any  further  existence  will  be  only  existence  of  a  par- 
ticular kind,  as  to  be  white,  etc.  Hence,  in  order  to  have  a 
single  substantial  existence,  and  so  a  substantial  unity  we 
must  have  one  substantial  form,  and  one  only.1 

1  Cf.  P.  Geny,  S.J.,  Gregorianum,  1925,  Vol.  VI,  pp.  126  f.  ;  and  Divus 
Thomas  (Plac),  1925,  pp.  72  f. 


SUBSTANTIAL  CHANGE  IN  GENERAL       133 

But,  are  there  in  the  world  any  beings  which  possess 
essential  unity  of  this  kind  P1  We  must  certainly  answer 
this  affirmatively,  both  because  of  our  consciousness  which 
affirms  that  we  are  such  unities  ourselves,  and  the  intolerable 
consequences  which  follow  from  splitting  up  human  nature 
into  two  or  more  natures — from  what  is  called  psychological 
dualism — and  because  in  the  world  of  inanimate  matter,  if 
we  were  to  deny  such  essential  unity  to  everything,  it  is 
clear  that  nothing  could  be  quantitative,  since,  having  no 
one  nature,  there  could  not  be  parts  of  one  nature,  and 
nothing  would  be  quantitative  and  extended.  The  hypo- 
thesis of  Leibniz  was  precisely  that  of  the  plurality  of  monads, 
of  substantial  forms,  and  we  agree  with  him  that  this  must 
logically  lead  to  a  denial  of  extension  :  a  denial  which  we 
have  seen  to  be  impossible,  and  which,  in  any  case,  no 
Scholastic,  not  even  those  who  hold  the  doctrine  of  the 
plurality  of  forms,  would  admit.  Thus,  the  individual  in  the 
organic  and  inorganic  worlds  must  be  granted  to  have  a 
unity  of  nature,  an  essential  unity,  otherwise  the  world  as  we 
know  it  becomes  inexplicable. 

S.  Thomas  argues  against  the  plurality  of  forms  in  the 
following  passages,  among  others  : 

Summa  Theologica,  Part  I,  Q.  76,  Arts.  3,  4,  6,  ad  ium,  8  ; 
Part  III,  Q.  1,  A.  5,  ad  ium.  Contra  Gentiles,  Lib.  II,  Caps. 
57>  58.  Questio  Disp.  De  Spiritualibus  Creaturis,  A.  1,  ad 
o,um  ;  A.  3  ;  Q.  Disp.  de  Anima,  A.  9  et  11  ;  Quodlibet  I, 
A.  6  ;  Quodlibet  XI,  A.  5  ;  de  Substantiis  Separatis,  Cap.  6  ; 
from  the  last  of  which  the  following  passage  may  be  quoted  : 

'  To  make  an  end  of  the  matter,  the  aforesaid  position  ' 
(i.e.  that  there  are  a  plurality  of  forms)  '  destroys  the  first 
principles  of  philosophy,  by  removing  unity  from  individuals, 
and  consequently  both  true  entity,  and  the  diversity  of 
things.  For  if  another  act  supervenes  to  something  which 
exists  in  act,  the  whole  will  not  be  a  unity  per  se,  but  only 
per  accidens,  for  the  reason  that  two  acts  or  forms  are  in 
themselves  diverse,  and  agree  only  in  the  subject ;  to  be 
one,  however,  through  the  unity  of  the  subject  is  to  be  one 
per  accidens.' 

1  Cf.  Geny,  Divus  Thomas,  loc.  cit.,  p.  74. 


134         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

Thus  he  always  appeals  to  the  principle  :  '  substantial 
form  gives  existence  simply  speaking  '  ;  so  that  anything 
added  can  only  give  accidental  existence,  with  the  result 
that  nothing  can  have  more  than  one  substantial  form. 

It  follows  immediately  from  this  that  the  opinion  of  Suarez, 
that  the  same  individual  accidents  remain  throughout  a 
substantial  change,  cannot  be  maintained  ;  for  if  substantial 
form  disappears  at  the  moment  of  change,  the  subsistence  of 
the  first  subject  which  constitutes  its  capacity  for  sustaining 
itself  also  disappears,  since  this  is  caused  by  substantial  form. 
So,  evidently,  if  the  substance  ceases  to  be  self-sustaining,  it 
ipso  facto  becomes  incapable  of  sustaining  or  supporting 
anything  else,  such  as  accidents,  which  must  therefore 
disappear  also  ;  to  suppose  the  contrary  would  be  like  sup- 
posing that  you  could  hang  your  hat  on  a  nail  that  wasn't 
there. 

Are  we,  then,  to  suppose  that  nothing  at  all  of  the  sub- 
stance which  undergoes  substantial  change  is  to  be  found  in 
the  new  substance  which  comes  into  being,  with  the  excep- 
tion of  the  absolutely  undetermined  first  matter  ?  This 
does  not  at  all  follow,  for  we  can  see  that  though  the  replace- 
ment of  one  substantial  form  by  another  is  instantaneous, 
yet  the  process  which  leads  up  to  this  change  is  a  gradual 
one  :  since  the  first  substance  is  gradually  changed  by  the 
modification  of  its  qualities  until  it  arrives  at  the  state  in 
which  the  new  substantial  form,  which  is  to  take  possession, 
is  required  as  the  source  of  these  modified  qualities.  The 
accidents  introduced  in  this  way  into  the  changing  substance 
are  called  by  the  Scholastics  the  previous  dispositions,  since 
they  dispose  the  subject  to  be  informed  by  a  new  form  ;  and 
these  remain  virtually  through  the  change,  since  the  matter 
which  has  been  brought,  by  their  means,  to  the  point  at 
which  it  calls  out,  as  it  were,  for  the  new  form,  remains 
throughout  the  change.  It  never  has  the  chance  to  fall  into 
complete  indetermination,  since  the  new  form  takes  posses- 
sion of  it  as  the  old  one  disappears.  They  are  like  children 
playing  '  musical  chairs,'  where  one  child  holds  on  to  the 
coat-tails  of  another,  so  as  to  be  able  to  occupy  immediately 
the  chair  which  the  other  has  vacated.    Consequently,  the 


SUBSTANTIAL  CHANGE  IN  GENERAL      135 

new  form  will  produce  in  the  substance  accidental  disposi- 
tions which  are  the  exact  counterpart  of  those  which  the 
subject  had,  immediately  before  the  change,  when  the  old 
substantial  form  was  present.  These  dispositions  will,  how- 
ever, be  numerically  distinct  from  the  previous  ones,  since  we 
now  have  a  new  subject.  They  are  called  the  proximate 
dispositions.  Can  these  latter  be  said  to  precede  the  sub- 
stantial form  ?  The  answer  is,  that,  regarded  from  different 
points  of  view,  they  precede  and  follow  it.  Inasmuch  as 
they  prepare  the  subject  for  the  reception  of  the  substantial 
form,  they  precede  it ;  for,  from  this  point  of  view,  they  are 
the  same  as  the  previous  dispositions,  which  affected  the 
matter  which  the  new  substantial  form  takes  possession  of ; 
but  they  follow  it,  inasmuch  as  it  is  due  to  the  new  sub- 
stantial form  that  they  are  able  to  be  supported  as  entities  of  a 
certain  nature.  Thus  they  precede  it  in  the  genus  of  material 
disposing  cause,  and  follow  it  in  the  genus  of  formal  cause  : 
according  to  the  general  principle  :  '  causa  ad  invicem  sunt 
causes  in  diverso  genere  ' — causes  which  are  mutual  causes  are 
causes  in  different  genera.  From  the  point  of  view  of  time, 
they  neither  precede  nor  follow  the  new  substantial  form,  but 
are  contemporaneous  with  its  coming,  since  this  occurs  instan- 
taneously. Hence,  we  see  that  matter  is  never  left  wholly 
undetermined,  even  for  a  moment,  whether  in  the  order  of 
time,  or  that  of  intelligibility.  If  difficulty  be  experienced 
in  conceiving  how  a  thing  may  both  precede  and  follow 
another,  and  yet  be  simultaneous  with  it,  the  following 
example,  though  inadequate,  may  be  a  help.  In  an  ecclesi- 
astical procession  the  dignitaries  walk  at  the  rear  of  it,  and 
so  follow  it ;  nevertheless  they  precede  all  the  other  mem- 
bers of  the  procession  in  dignity,  and  are  at  the  same  time 
simultaneous  with  them  all  in  walking,  since  the  whole  pro- 
cession moves  together  at  the  same  time.  Thus  they  follow 
in  space,  precede  in  dignity,  and  are  simultaneous  in  time. 

Question  II.     The  Source  of  the  New  Substantial  Form  in 
Generation. 
What  has  been  said  about  the  '  dispositions  '  introduced 
into  the  changing  body  will  suggest  that  the  new  substantial 


136         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

form  takes  its  rise  from  the  changing  material  thing  itself ; 
and  this  is,  in  fact,  the  Thomistic  opinion,  which  is  expressed 
in  the  phrase  :  '  material  forms  are  produced  (educuntur) 
from  the  potentiality  of  matter.'  The  process  may  be 
likened — if  proper  care  be  taken  not  to  press  the  comparison 
too  far — to  the  felling  of  a  tree.  Little  by  little,  as  the  axe 
bites  into  the  trunk,  the  tree  becomes  less  capable  of  preser- 
ving its  upright  position,  until  finally  the  moment  comes 
when  it  is  unable  to  stand  any  longer  ;  a  slight  stroke,  the 
tree  wavers  and  comes  crashing  down.  Similarly,  a  body 
which  is  undergoing  a  substantial  change  has  its  capacity  for 
preserving  its  original  nature  gradually  weakened  until 
finally  it,  as  it  were,  topples  over  into  the  arms  of  the  new 
form,  which  comes  to  it,  not  from  without,  but  from  within, 
as  a  result  of  its  natural  propensities  having  been  gradually 
altered.  This  process  is  held  by  S.  Thomas  to  be  verified 
only  in  the  case  of  material  forms,  not  of  spiritual  ones  ; 
since  only  the  former  are  dependent  on  matter  for  their 
existence,  and  consequently  these  alone  can  be  dependent 
on  it  for  their  actual  coming  into  being.  Evidently,  also, 
the  process  applies  only  to  substantial  generation,  not  to  the 
beginning  of  all  things. 

There  are,  however,  two  other  opposing  theories  as  to  the 
way  in  which  substantial  forms  come  to  be  ;  between  which 
the  Aristotelean  theory  stands  as  on  an  eminence,  preserving 
the  truth  of  both,  and  filling  in  their  lacunae. 

So,  some  thought  that  all  forms  actually  existed  in  matter, 
but  lay  hid  in  it ;  while  others  supposed  that  they  were  not 
in  matter  at  all,  but  were  created  whenever  substantial 
change  occurred. 

The  first  view  is,  according  to  S.  Thomas,1  erroneous,  as 
we  have  already  seen  ;  the  error  arising  from  a  failure  to 
distinguish  between  potency  and  act ;  since  the  forms  are 
potentially  only  in  the  matter,  not  actually ;  while  the 
second  is  also  erroneous,  since  it  implies  that  a  form  is,  in 
itself,  a  complete  being,  not  a  principle  of  being.  It  is,  in 
fact,  the  new  compound  which  comes  to  be,  not  form  alone, 
as  we  noticed  earlier  (cf.  p.  129). 

1  Cf.  Summa  Theologica,  Pars  I,  Q.  45,  a.  8  ;  and  VII  Metaphys., 
Lect.  7,  ed.  Cathala,  Nos.  1430  and  1431. 


SUBSTANTIAL  CHANGE  IN  GENERAL       137 

It  is,  however,  not  easy  to  see  how  the  new  substantial 
form  is  made  actual,  if,  as  we  have  just  said,  it  is  only 
potentially  in  matter,  and  is  not  created  ;  for  since  matter 
contains  it  only  potentially,  it  cannot  make  it  actual ;  and 
the  efficient  cause,  or  agent,  by  whose  means  the  change  is 
brought  about,  seems  also  incapable  of  doing  this.  The 
principle  of  causality  demands  that  a  cause  must  contain 
the  effect  at  least  virtually,  and  that  in  a  way  which  is  at 
least  equal  in  perfection  to  the  effect  itself.  This  condition 
is  not,  however,  verified  in  the  case  of  many  of  the  agents 
which  appear  to  produce  substantial  changes,  as  heat  or 
electricity,  which  can  hardly  be  said  to  contain  virtually  the 
forms  of  the  bodies  produced  by  their  means.  And  how  can 
a  bullet  be  thought  to  contain  virtually  the  forms  which 
appear  in  the  dead  body  of  the  man  whom  it  kills  ?  So, 
neither  matter  nor  yet  the  agent  seem  to  be  causes  which 
are  capable  of  producing  the  new  substantial  forms.  Besides 
this,  there  is  a  further  difficulty  in  supposing  that  the  new 
form  is  produced  by  the  agent,  since  the  action  of  an  agent 
is  an  accident,  and  so  cannot  produce  substance.  Aristotle 
thought  that  the  '  heavenly  bodies '  exercise  a  general 
influence  on  all  terrestrial  operations,  and  that  they  are 
beings  of  a  higher  order  than  earthly  bodies,  so  that  their 
power  virtually  contained  all  earthly  forms.  This  view  is 
obviously  untenable,  but  some  Scholastics,  thinking  that  an 
absolutely  general  cause  of  a  higher  order  to  that  of  parti- 
cular material  substances  is  required,  have  substituted  for 
the  influence  of  the  '  first  heaven  '  either  that  of  God,  or  of 
the  all-pervading  ether.  The  first  is  the  suggestion  of  M.  Nys 
in  his  Cosmologie  ;x  the  second  that  of  Remer.2 

In  M.  Nys'  view  the  Divine  action  is  required  at  the 
moment  when  the  forms  appear,  not  by  way  of  creation, 
but  as  giving  to  the  generative  forces  the  necessary  perfec- 
tion ;  while  Remer  thinks  that  the  ether  of  space,  being  the 
subject  of  all  physical  action,  may  be  considered  as  a  universal 
agent,  and  so  as  containing  virtually,  and  on  the  same  level 
as  themselves,  the  forms  of  all  other  bodies. 

1  Nys,  Cosmologie,  Tome  II,  pp.  178  ff. 

2  Remer,  Cosmologia,  ed.  4a  (1921),  pp.  83  ft'.,  No.  54,  versus  finem. 


138         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

Neither  of  these  suggestions,  however,  seems  altogether 
satisfactory,  for  to  invoke  a  special  action  of  God  every  time 
a  generation  takes  place,  and  when  unable  to  see  any  natural 
explanation  of  a  natural  event,  to  cut  the  knot  by  asserting 
that  it  must  be  due  to  the  action  of  God,  seems  to  make  of 
Him  a  '  Deus  ex  machina.'  It  is  as  if  a  savage,  falling  into  a 
river,  and  being  swept  away  by  it,  were  to  say  '  the  god  of 
the  river  has  got  hold  of  me,'  not  knowing  the  law  of  gravita- 
tion ;  but  what  is  pardonable  in  a  savage  is  hardly  so  in  a 
philosopher. 

Nor  is  Remer's  theory  much  more  probable,  for  even  if 
there  be  a  material  ether  of  the  kind  supposed,  which  is 
highly  doubtful,  its  characteristics  are  so  negative,  since  it 
is  thought  of  merely  as  the  medium  whereby  electro-magnetic 
waves  are  transmitted,  that  it  can  hardly  be  considered  to 
be  an  active  agent  of  the  kind  required. 

The  solution  seems  rather  to  be  found  in  a  careful  and 
strictly  philosophical  consideration  of  the  parts  played  in  the 
process  of  substantial  change  by  the  material  which  under- 
goes it,  and  the  agent  which  modifies  this  material,  as  well  as 
by  the  active  character  of  substance  itself.  According  to 
this  view,  the  agent  which  introduces  into  the  changing 
bodies  the  dispositions  favourable  to  the  coming  of  the  new 
substantial  forms  does  not  produce  or  effect  these  forms,  but 
merely  gives  the  matter  that  actuation  which  is  necessary 
for  the  transformation  of  its  capacity  for  them  into  actual 
possession  of  them.  So,  absolutely  speaking,  a  sculptor  has 
no  need  formally  to  possess  the  form  of  the  statue  which  he 
is  carving ;  nor  even  virtually,  except  in  the  sense  that  he 
has  the  power,  both  mental,  by  reason  of  his  artistic  con- 
ception, and  physical,  so  to  manipulate  his  material  that  in 
it  the  statue  may  appear.  The  statue  which  results  depends 
therefore  both  on  the  material  used,  e.g.  whether  it  be 
marble  or  wood,  and  on  the  power  of  the  sculptor.  Similarly, 
in  the  case  of  natural  agents,  both  the  matter  which  is  being 
changed,  and  the  agent  which  is  introducing  modifications 
into  it,  concur  in  the  production  of  the  new  substantial  com- 
pound, though  in  different  ways  :  for  the  agent  modifies  the 
substance,  which,  when  so  modified,  gives  birth,  as  it  were, 


SUBSTANTIAL  CHANGE  IN  GENERAL       139 

to  the  new  form.  It  is,  therefore,  the  material  substance,  as 
modified  by  the  agent,  which  possesses  virtually  the  new 
form  which  is  to  arise  in  it  ;  and  the  objections  raised  to  the 
virtual  possession  of  this  form  by  the  efficient  cause  of  the 
change  fall  to  the  ground.  That  this  is  true  seems  to  be 
borne  out  by  the  fact  that  a  random  application  of  the  effi- 
cient cause  will  not  produce  the  new  substance  ;  the  old 
must  be  modified  in  a  particular  manner,  i.e.  the  modifica- 
tions must  be  such  as  to  bring  it  to  the  state  in  which  it 
possesses  the  new  form  virtually.  So,  an  electrical  current 
has  to  be  applied  to  oxygen  and  hydrogen  in  a  particular 
way  in  order  to  make  them  combine  into  water  ;  and  it  is 
only  certain  lesions  or  diseases  which  cause  death.  Thus,  it 
is  not  necessary  to  suppose  that  electricity  or  a  bullet  possess 
virtually  the  forms  which  are  educed  by  their  means,  except 
in  the  sense  that  they  are  necessary  in  order  to  modify  the 
material  in  a  suitable  manner.  But  it  will  still  be  objected 
that  the  actions  which  cause  such  modifications  are  accidents, 
and  cannot  therefore  produce  substantial  forms,  but  only 
accidental  ones,  viz.  these  very  modifications.  This,  how- 
ever, is  easily  answered,  since  they  are  the  actions  of  sub- 
stance, and  are  naturally  united  to  it,  in  such  a  way  that  it 
acts  with  and  through  them.  The  power  manifested  in  the 
action  of  any  agent  is  not  the  power  of  the  action,  but  that 
of  the  agent  ;  being  nothing  else  than  the  power  or  force  of 
the  active  substance.  So,  as  Cajetan  says  :  '  Accidentalis  vis 
non  sua,  sed  substantia  est  virtus  '  ;  so  there  is  no  reason  why 
it  should  not  produce  a  substantial  actuation.  The  substance 
does  not  lie  inert  or  inactive  under  accidents  which  act  for  it, 
like  sentries  who  drive  away  intruders  from  the  sleeping 
camp  ;  but  they  are,  as  Cajetan  puts  it,  '  organa  conjuncta,' 
whose  whole  efficacy  is  that  of  the  substance  whose  '  organs  ' 
they  are.  Thus,  as  far  as  virtual  possession  of  the  new  form 
is  concerned,  we  can  say  that  this  is  found  in  the  changing 
material ;  and  as  far  as  it  is  necessary  that  this  material 
should  receive  a  new  substantial  actuation,  passing  from  the 
capacity  for  being  a  new  substance  to  being  it  actually,  such 
actuation  is  derived  from  the  agent,  whose  accidents  act 
with  its  own  substantial  power.     So  the  formal  or  specific 


i4o         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

character  of  the  substantial  form  is  educed  from  the  poten- 
tiality of  matter  ;  while  its  substantial  character  is  derived 
from  the  substantial  agent,  imparting  its  substantial  power 
to  its  accidents. 

These  remarks  seem  to  express  Cajetan's  view  as  he  sug- 
gests it  in  his  commentaries  on  the  first  part  of  the  Summa. 
Cf.  Comm.  in  lam  Partem,  Q.  54,  A.  3  ;  Nos.  8,  16,  and  17  ; 
in  Part  I.,  Q.  yy,  A.  1 ;  No.  13.  Cf.  Goudin,  Physica,  Pars  I, 
Disp.  2,  Q.  4,  A.  3  versus  finem. 


CHAPTER  XI 

SUBSTANTIAL    CHANGE    IN    CHEMICAL    COMPOSITION  I 
THE    QUESTION   OF   MIXTURES 

Current  Scientific  Views — Philosophical  Views — Thomist  Opinions 
as  to  the  Permanence  of  the  Elements  and  Qualities  in  Mixtures. 

In  the  general  discussion  of  the  theory  of  matter  and  form 
we  noticed  that  some  modern  Scholastics  refuse  to  admit 
that  substantial  change  actually  occurs,  owing  to  the  diffi- 
culties which  have  arisen  from  the  discoveries  made  in 
modern  times  by  physical  science.  These  difficulties  are 
particularly  acute  with  regard  to  inorganic  chemical  com- 
pounds, which  the  Scholastics  call  '  mixtures  ' — though  the 
name  is  not  absolutely  confined  to  the  inorganic  realm — and 
some  authors  who  are  willing  to  allow  substantial  change  to 
organic  things  refuse  to  admit  it  in  the  case  of  the  inorganic. 
In  the  present  discussion  we  shall  confine  ourselves  to  a 
consideration  of  inorganic  bodies  ;  and  even  so  it  will  be 
impossible  to  consider  in  detail  all  the  difficulties  which  can 
be  raised  from  the  point  of  view  of  physical  science,  since  we 
are  concerned  to  unwind  the  thread  which  may  lead  a  begin- 
ner safely  through  the  labyrinth  of  Scholastic  philosophy, 
not  to  examine  all  the  obscurities  of  its  caverns  ;  and  because 
such  a  consideration  would  entail  a  course  of  physical  science 
which  is  outside  the  scope  of  a  brief  philosophical  summary, 
such  as  the  present.  We  will  therefore  try  to  see  what  are 
the  main  philosophical  ideas  and  principles  which  lead  to  the 
solution  of  these  difficulties. 

As  is  well  known,  all  inorganic  bodies  are  regarded  by 
science  as  aggregates  of  smaller  ones,  composite  bodies  being 
collections  qf  molecules,  which  are  themselves  collections  of 
two  or  more  particles  of  the  simple  elements,  which  are 
called  atoms.    In  both  cases,  therefore,  gross  matter,  whether 

141 


142         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

composite — what  is  called  by  the  Scholastics  a  mixture — or 
simple,  which  we  may  take  for  the  present  as  meaning  the 
chemical  elements,  is  composed  of  a  number  of  discrete  par- 
ticles in  juxtaposition.  Even  so,  we  have  not  come  to  the 
end  of  the  division  of  matter  as  envisaged  by  physics,  for 
the  atom  itself  is  regarded  as  being  composed  of  parts  :  the 
proton,  which  is  a  positive  electric  charge,  and  electrons, 
which  are  negative  unit  charges.  The  number  of  these 
electrons  is  held  to  vary  in  the  different  chemical  elements  ; 
beginning  with  hydrogen,  which  has  one  electron,  and  so  a 
positive  unit  charge  as  proton,  up  to  uranium  which  has 
ninety-two  electrons.  Hence,  according  to  this  view,  all 
matter  is  fundamentally  the  same,  being  composed  of  a 
greater  or  less  number  of  electrical  units. 

Faced  by  this  theory,  which  seems  well-established 
scientifically,  some  Scholastics  thought  that  the  traditional 
view,  that  inorganic  substances  differ  in  kind,  ought  to  be 
abandoned,  and  along  with  it,  of  course,  the  idea  of  the 
essential  unity  of  inorganic  bodies.  Some  of  these  writers 
thought  that  the  essential  unity  of  organic  beings  (i.e.  living 
ones)  could  still  be  maintained,  but  others  more  logically 
(e.g.  P.  Descoqs,  S.J.)  abandoned  this  also.  For,  in  fact,  if 
the  reasons  which  cause  us  to  give  up  the  idea  that  the 
elements  of  inorganic  matter  do  not  remain  actually  in  the 
compound, — and  so  the  essential  unity  of  compounds, — are 
peremptory  in  the  inorganic  realm,  they  will  be  so  also  when 
these  substances,  exhibiting  the  same  characteristics,  are 
found  in  living  things,  as  is  in  fact  the  case.  The  theory, 
however,  that  living  things  are  not  essential  unities  leads  to 
very  serious  difficulties  both  philosophical,  and,  as  Professor 
J.  S.  Haldane  has  pointed  out,  scientific.  Nevertheless,  it  is 
such  thorough-going  sacrifice  of  unity  which  the  scientific 
theory,  if  it  is  to  be  taken  at  its  face  value,  seems  to  demand. 

We  are  therefore  led  to  ask  whether  the  traditional  view 
may  not,  after  all,  be  the  true  one  :  i.e.  whether  chemically 
simple  bodies,  those,  namely,  which  are  not  composed  of 
other  chemical  elements,  do  actually  persist  as  such  when 
they  join  together  to  form  a  compound. 

What   are   known   by   the   physicists   as   the   chemical 


CHANGE  IN  CHEMICAL  COMPOUNDS       143 

elements,  of  which  ninety-two  are  supposed  to  exist,  and  of 
which  ninety  have  at  present  been  discovered,  are  not  in 
fact  all  chemically  simple,  though  they  are  usually  treated 
as  if  they  were.  For  our  purpose  it  will  be  sufficient  to  con- 
sider them  as  simple,  since,  if  we  can  show  that  these 
elements  cannot  retain  their  own  nature  in  composition,  the 
same  reasons  will  apply  to  the  constituents  of  those  elements 
which  are,  in  fact,  composite. 

Since  the  chemical  elements  naturally  combine  with  one 
another,  those  which  do  so  must  have  a  natural  tendency  to 
do  so,  or,  as  it  is  called,  have  affinity  for  one  another.  Their 
power  to  combine  is  known  as  their  valency,  so  that  an  atom 
which  combines  with  one,  two,  three,  etc.,  atoms  of  another 
element  is  called  mono-valent,  di-valent,  tri-valent,  and  so 
on.  The  result  of  such  a  combination  will  be  an  equilibrium, 
and  the  question  is,  how  is  this  equilibrium  to  be  explained 
philosophically. 

Broadly  speaking,  there  are  two  opinions  at  present  in 
vogue  among  Scholastic  writers.  The  first  is  that  of  the 
pluriformists  who  trace  their  philosophical  descent  to  S. 
Albert  the  Great.  The  second  is  the  Thomistic  view,  which 
maintains  that  in  many  compounds  the  elements  of  which  it 
is  made  up  do  not  remain  substantially,  or  as  such,  when 
mixed  together.  They  are  not  present  in  the  mixture  actually 
and  formally,  -but  virtually  only,  by  means  of  a  persistence 
of  their  qualities. 

The  opponents  of  this  view  urge,  in  addition  to  the  general 
scientific  argument  touched  on  above,  the  further  considera- 
tion that  it  is  difficult,  if  not  impossible,  to  see  why  a 
chemical  compound  possessed  of  a  single  form  or  nature 
which  is  different  from  those  of  its  elements,  should  invari- 
ably be  able  to  be  resolved  again  into  these  elements,  as  we 
know  that  in  fact  it  can  be  ;  and  moreover,  why,  if  it  is  an 
undifferentiated  unity,  different  agents  acting  on  it  do  not 
produce  different  effects,  whereas,  in  fact,  such  different 
agents  as  electricity,  heat,  or  even  a  blow,  all  produce  the 
same  effect  of  resolving  the  compound  once  more  into  its 
constituent  elements.  All  these  phenomena,  they  contend, 
are  easily  and  naturally  explained  on  the  hypothesis  that  the 


144         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

compound  is  a  mere  aggregate  of  atoms.  In  addition  many 
other  arguments  are  brought  forward  against  the  Thomistic 
opinion,  such  as  the  impossibility  of  accidental  forms  pro- 
ducing substantial  ones,  of  which  we  spoke  above  :  as  well 
as  many  special  difficulties  relating  to  particular  classes  of 
chemical  substances.  We  must,  therefore,  see  what  answer 
the  Thomists  make  to  these  objections,  and  why  in  spite  of 
them,  they  are  so  determined  in  maintaining  that  the 
elements  do  not  remain  actually  in  the  mixture. 

To  explain  the  resolution  of  the  chemical  compound  into 
its  elements,  modern  Thomists  develop  further  what  they 
mean  by  saying  that  the  elements  remain  virtually  in  the 
mixture. 

This  virtual  permanence  of  the  elements  may  mean  either  : 

i.  That  neither  their  substance  nor  their  qualities  remain 
formally  in  the  mixture,  or  : 

2.  That  while  the  substances  do  not  remain  formally,  the 
qualities  do  so  ;  and  this  again  may  be  understood  in  two 
senses  : 

(a)  That  the  qualities  which  remain  are  homogeneous 
throughout  the  whole  mixture  or  compound,  or  : 

(b)  That  they  are  localised  in  different  parts  of  it,  so  that 
the  compound  is  heterogeneous  with  respect  to  its  qualities, 
having  one  quality  in  one  part,  and  another  in  another. 

(i)  With  regard  to  the  first  view,  it  is  further  explained  as 
follows  :  The  chemical  compound  is  perfectly  homogeneous, 
and  contains  all  the  material  bases  of  the  elements,  which  are 
moulded  into  a  higher  unity  by  means  of  the  one  specific 
principle.  This  form  of  the  compound  is  virtually  many, 
inasmuch  as  it  takes  the  place  of  the  various  substantial 
forms  of  the  elements.  The  qualities  of  the  elements  are 
thought  to  persist  virtually  in  the  compound  in  so  far  as 
their  opposing  qualities  are  represented  in  it  by  some  third 
quality  which  is  their  mean,  and  the  mean  qualities  so 
formed  are  considered  to  be  distributed  evenly  throughout 
the  whole  compound,  in  such  a  way  that  it  has  a  single 
electrical  force,  a  single  luminous  force,  a  single  calorific 
force,  and  so  on  ;  which  single  forces  represent,  though,  of 
course,  they  are  not  the  same  as  the  corresponding  forces  of 


CHANGE   IN  CHEMICAL  COMPOUNDS        145 

the  elements.  The  compound  is  thus  perfectly  homogeneous, 
both  substantially  and  accidentally. 

(2)  (a)  The  second  view  in  its  first  form  is  that  put  for- 
ward by  Fr.  J.  Gredt,  O.S.B.1  It  differs  from  the  view  just 
given  in  that  he  holds  that  the  qualities  of  the  elements 
remain  formally  in  the  compound,  i.e.  that  the  electrical 
force  of  each  of  the  elements  occurs  again  in  the  compound, 
and  is  not  replaced  by  a  single  third  quality  which  is  their 
mean.  Nevertheless,  it  agrees  with  the  previous  view  in 
maintaining  that  these  qualities  are  evenly  distributed 
throughout  the  whole  mass  of  the  compound.  Thus  the 
intensity  of  the  qualities  of  the  elements  will  be  diminished 
until  a  state  of  equilibrium  is  reached,  owing  to  the  action 
of  the  elements  on  one  another,  but  the  nature  of  these 
qualities  will  remain  the  same.  Hence  the  compound  will 
have  a  single  substantial  form,  and  a  variety  of  qualities 
which  are  of  the  same  kind  as  those  of  the  elements.  These 
qualities  have  a  uniform  intensity  which  is  less  than  the 
intensity  of  the  qualities  of  the  elements,  the  qualities  them- 
selves being  found  equally,  both  as  regards  their  natures  and 
their  intensities,  in  all  parts  of  the  compound,  which  will 
thus  be  perfectly  homogeneous,  both  substantially  and 
accidentally.  This  qualitative  homogeneity  is,  however, 
mitigated  to  some  extent  by  the  admission  of  a  quantitative 
heterogeneity  in-  the  compound,  i.e.  a  heterogeneity  of 
structure.  \ 

(2)  (b)  The  second  form  of  the  second  view  goes  further  in 
the  admission  of  accidental  heterogeneity  within  the  com- 
pound ;  for,  while  still  maintaining  that  there  is  a  single 
substantial  form  in  the  compound,  it  allows  that  its  qualities 
are  of  the  same  nature  as  those  of  the  elements,  and,  more- 
over, that  they  are  found  in  the  mixture  in  groups,  which  are 
localised  in  different  parts  of  it.  As  regards  their  intensity, 
it  agrees  with  the  previous  view.  This  is  the  theory  proposed 
by  M.  Nys.2 

The  view  that  the  qualities  remain  formally  in  the  mixture, 
as  opposed  to  that  which  says  they  remain  virtually  only,  by 

1  Elementa  Philosophies  (ed.  4),  Vol.  I,  Nos.  405-408. 

2  Nys,  Cosmologie  (ed.  4),  Vol.  II,  pp.  206  ft.,  Nos.  169  ff. 


146  MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

means  of  some  third  mean  quality,  is  now  almost  universally 
accepted  among  Thomists  :  for  the  reason  that  it  seems 
impossible  on  the  latter  view  to  account  for  the  reappearance 
of  the  elements  at  the  dissolution  of  the  compound.  For 
it  is  a  principle  of  hylomorphism  that  a  form  cannot  appear 
except  in  matter  which  is  predisposed  to  receive  it.  The 
theory  of  the  mean  quality,  however,  renders  such  pre- 
disposition absolutely  impossible,  for  if  the  compound  is 
altogether  homogeneous,  both  substantially  and  accidentally, 
it  is  impossible  that  it  should  be  predisposed  in  one  part  in  a 
different  way  to  that  in  which  it  is  predisposed  in  another  ; 
and  so  the  appearance  of  two  or  more  distinct  forms  is 
excluded. 

To  show  that  the  elements  do  not  retain  their  own  nature 
in  the  mixture,  or,  in  other  words,  that  the  mixture  is  a  new 
entity  with  a  nature  of  its  own,  distinct  from  those  of  its 
components,  the  Thomists  argue  from  its  distinctive  charac- 
teristics and  operations.  If  we  find  in  any  body,  or  class 
of  bodies,  characteristics  peculiar  to  that  body  or  class,  and 
such  as  are  found  in  no  others,  it  is  permissible,  and  indeed 
unavoidable,  to  conclude  that  such  characteristics  are 
properties  of  it,  since,  if  they  did  not  arise  from  the  very 
nature  of  the  body — which  is  the  meaning  of  the  word 
property — they  would  be  without  reason  of  being ;  for,  as 
they  are  constant,  they  must  owe  their  being  to  some  con- 
stant factor  in  the  situation,  and  the  only  constant  one  is 
the  natures  of  the  bodies  themselves.  Now,  in  mixtures, 
this  is  just  what  we  do  find,  for  along  with  some  qualities 
which  were  present  in  their  elements  we  also  find  many 
which  were  not  present  there,  and  are  really  new  ;  qualities, 
moreover,  which  attach  to  certain  mixtures  exclusively  and 
constantly.  Such  are  colour,  taste,  scent,  chemical  affinities, 
etc.  For  example,  some  compounds  such  as  sulphate  of 
barium,  are  stable  and  absolutely  inert,  though  its  elements 
are  very  active,1  and  new  characteristics  are  produced  by 
hydration,  which  renders  acids  capable  of  dissolving  metals, 
etc.,  which  their  components  could  not  do.  M.  Nys  says  that 
thousands  of  such  modifications,  which  are  more  or  less  pro- 

1  Cf.  Nys,  Cosmologie,  Vol.  II,  p.  231. 


CHANGE  IN  CHEMICAL  COMPOUNDS        147 

found,  have  been  observed,  and  the  reader  may  be  referred 
to  his  work  for  many  more  examples.1  We  shall  decide 
whether  any  substance  which  is  under  consideration  is  a 
true  compound,  in  accordance  with  our  observation  of  such 
changes  in  particular  mixtures  ;  and  it  is  also  to  be  noted 
that  what  is  important,  from  the  philosophical  point  of  view, 
in  the  properties  observed  in  compounds  is  not  their  physical 
analysis,  but  the  way  in  which  they  operate.  Scientifically 
speaking,  all  we  can  know  of  these  properties  is  such  aspects 
of  them  as  are  amenable  to  quantitative  treatment,  and  so 
are  measurable,  but  the  philosopher  ought  to  take  into 
account  their  operation  as  a  whole,  including  the  effects 
which  they  produce  on  other  bodies  ;  since  their  operation 
and  mode  of  working  taken  as  a  whole  is  the  only  means  we 
have  of  discovering  their  nature.  Science,  by  reason  of  its 
method,  which  is  mathematical,  does  not  find  it  necessary 
to  take  account  of  the  ends  towards  which  things  tend,  or 
their  purposes,  nor  even  why  they  occur  in  the  way  they  do, 
but  philosophy  must  consider  all  these  elements,  if  it  is  to 
arrive  at  a  balanced  view  of  the  natures  of  things.  If  this  is 
done,  we  shall  find  that  the  compounds  often  behave  in  a 
way  very  different  from  that  of  their  elements ;  and  naturally 
tend  to  different  ends.  These  considerations,  then,  as  to  the 
operations  and  intrinsic  tendencies  of  the  elements  and  com- 
pounds show  that  the  elements  are  specifically  distinct  one 
from  another,  and  the  compounds  also  from  their  elements.  It 
is  altogether  illogical  to  admit  a  specific  distinction  among  the 
elements,  and  to  deny  it  as  between  elements  and  compounds, 
since  the  same  criterion  which  assures  us  of  the  one,  viz. 
diversity  of  operations,  is  equally  decisive  in  the  case  of  the 
other. 

If,  then,  the  elements  are  specifically  changed  when  they 
combine,  so  that  they  do  not  remain  in  the  compound  for- 
mally, how  are  we  to  explain  the  fact  that  the  compound 
shows  many  of  their  characteristics,  or  the  sum  of  them,  such 
as  weight,  and  is  always  resolvable  into  them  again  ? 

As  we  have  already  seen,  the  Thomists  agree  in  saying 
that  the  qualities  of  the  elements  remain  formally,  i.e. 
1  Nys,  op.  cit.,  Vol.  II,  pp.  227-239. 
L 


148         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

retaining  their  original  nature,  in  the  compound.  If  they 
did  not,  they  would  either  be  represented  by  a  quality  which 
is  their  mean,  or  potentially  only,  or  not  at  all.  The  last 
hypothesis  makes  it  quite  impossible  to  explain  how  it  is  that 
many  qualities  of  the  compound  are  merely  the  sum  of  those 
of  the  elements,  the  fact  that  the  spectrum  of  the  molecule 
shows  the  characteristic  spectra  of  the  elements,  and  the 
fact  that  the  compound  is  always  resolvable  into  its  elements. 
If  they  remain  potentially  only,  different  external  agents, 
which  dissolve  the  compound,  would  produce  different  results, 
since  the  only  determining  factor  in  this  case  would  be  the 
agent.  This,  however,  is  not  the  case,  for  whatever  agent  be 
employed,  the  resulting  elements  are  always  the  same.  We 
have  already  seen  that  the  theory  of  a  mean  quality  cannot 
be  maintained,  and  so  we  must  conclude  that  the  qualities 
remain  in  the  compound  formally.  If  this  be  so  is  it  sufficient, 
in  order  to  account  for  the  facts,  to  say  that  they  are  dis- 
tributed evenly  and  homogeneously  throughout  the  whole 
compound,  their  capacity  for  reappearance  in  the  solution  of 
it  being  accounted  for  by  its  being  heterogeneous  in  struc- 
ture, i.e.  that  there  is  a  difference  of  arrangement  of  parts  in 
one  portion  of  the  compound  from  that  in  another  ?  It 
seems  very  improbable  that  such  a  heterogeneity  as  this  is 
sufficient,  since  it  is  quantitative  only,  and  thus  seems  to  be 
inadequate  as  a  predisposition  for  the  appearance  of  sub- 
stantial forms  which  differ  in  kind,  and  which  must,  there- 
fore, be  prepared  for  by  qualitative  differences.  It  does  not 
seem  possible  to  regard  inanimate  bodies  as  wholly  unified 
and  unorganised,  as  was  done  in  the  Middle  Ages,  but  rather 
we  find  in  them  an  organisation  which  is  comparable  to  that 
of  living  things,  though  less  elaborate.  Thus,  the  view  which 
ascribes  to  the  molecule  different  qualities  in  its  different 
parts  appears  more  consonant  with  the  known  fUcts,  and  on 
a  wide  view  more  acceptable,  than  that  which  denies  it  : 
since  we  shall  recognise  right  through  the  material  world, 
from  the  atom  up  to  the  highest  forms  of  life,  a  continually 
increasing  heterogeneity  of  structure  and  quality,  along  with 
a  consistent  homogeneity  of  nature.  To  maintain  such  a 
gradual  ascent  is  merely  an  expansion  of  the  Thomistic 


CHANGE  IN  CHEMICAL  COMPOUNDS        149 

notion  of  the  scale  of  being  of  which  Milton  speaks  in 
Paradise  Lost  (Bk.  V,  lines  468  fi.)  : 

To  whom  the  winged  Hierarch  repli'd. 
O  Adam,  one  Almightie  is,  from  whom 
All  things  proceed,  and  up  to  him  return, 
If  not  depraved  from  good,  created  all 
Such  to  perfection,  one  first  matter  all, 
Indu'd  with  various  forms,  various  degrees 
Of  substance,  and  in  things  that  live,  of  life  ; 
But  more  refin'd,  more  spirituous,  and  pure, 
As  neerer  to  him  plac't,  or  neerer  tending 
Each  in  their  several  active  Sphears  assignd, 
Till  body  up  to  spirit  work,  in  bounds 
Proportiond  to  each  kind.     So  from  the  root 
Springs  lighter  the  green  stalk,  from  thence  the  leaves 
More  a^rie,  last  the  bright  consummate  floure 
Spirits  odorous  breathes  :    flours  and  thir  fruit 
Man's  nourishment,  by  gradual  scale  sublim'd 
To  vital  spirits  aspire,  to  animal 
To  intellectual,  give  both  life  and  sense, 
Fansie  and  understanding,  whence  the  soule 
Reason  receives,  and  reason  is  her  being. 

Somewhat  the  same  idea,  though  carried  much  farther,  is 
held  as  true  by  Professor  Whitehead,  who  says  :  '  The  doc- 
trine which  I  am  maintaining  is  that  the  whole  concept  of 
materialism  only  applies  to  very  abstract  entities,  the 
products  of  logical  discernment.  The  concrete  enduring 
entities  are  organisms,  so  that  the  plan  of  the  whole  influences 
the  very  characters  of  the  various  subordinate  organisms 
which  enter  into  it.  In  the  case  of  an  animal,  the  mental 
states  enter  into  the  plan  of  the  total  organism  and  thus 
modify  the  plans  of  the  successive  subordinate  organisms 
until  the  ultimate  smallest  organisms,  such  as  electrons,  are 
reached.  Thus  an  electron  within  a  living  body  is  different 
from  an  electron  outside  it,  by  reason  of  the  plan  of  the  body. 
.  .  .  But  the  principle  of  modification  is  perfectly  general 
throughout  nature,  and  represents  no  property  peculiar  to 
living  bodies.'1 

The  difficulties  arising  from  the  existence  of  isomeric  and 
polymeric  substances,2  as  well  as  the  phenomena  of  allotropy,3 

1  Science  and  the  Modern  World,  pp.  98  fi.  ;  cf.  pp.  164  fi.  Cf.  also 
Nys,  Vol.  II,  pp.  200  fi.  ;  Geny  in  Gregorianum  (1922),  pp.  458  f.  ;  Divus 
Thomas  (Plac.)  (1925),  p.  77. 

*  Cf.  Nys,  Vol.  II,  pp.  268  fi.  8  Ibid.,  Vol.  I,  pp.  240  f. 


150         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

can  be  explained  on  these  principles  ;  while  the  assertion 
that  atomic  weight,  mass,  etc.,  remain  constant  does  not 
affect  our  conclusion,  since  we  maintain  that  the  same  matter 
remains  throughout  the  change,  and  so  those  accidents  which 
are  quantitive,  and  thus  directly  associated  with  matter,  will 
naturally  remain  unchanged  also. 

In  general  it  is  true  to  say  that  all  the  facts  which  science 
takes  as  proving  the  essential  discontinuity  of  matter — since 
this  is  the  simplest  hypothesis,  and  therefore  for  science  the 
truest — can  equally  well  be  accounted  for  by  substantial 
homogeneity,  together  with  accidental  heterogeneity.  We 
are  led  to  adopt  this  latter  view  from  the  philosophical  con- 
sideration of  the  natural  intrinsic  tendencies  of  bodies  and 
their  relations  with  the  rest  of  the  material  universe  :  con- 
siderations which  natural  science  does  not,  and  ought  not, 
to  take  into  account  j1  dealing  as  it  does  only  with  measur- 
able phenomena. 

1  Examples  of  the  application  of  these  principles  are  to  be  found  in 
Hcenen's  Cosmologia,  pp.  350-404  ;  e.g.  p.  368  with  regard  to  Bragg's 
experiments.    See  also  his  Summary,  pp.  401  ff. 


CHAPTER   XII 

THE   INDIVIDUAL 

Its  Nature — Opinions — Explanation  of  the  Thomist  View — Reasons 
in  its  Favour — Meaning  of  '  Materia  Signata  ' — Some  Diffi- 
culties Considered. 

So  far,  we  have  been  concerned  with  general  natures  ;  first  of 
material  substances,  and  then  of  its  various  species  and 
accidental  characteristics  ;  and  we  now  have  to  turn  to  the 
individuals  which  belong  to  these  species.  It  is  with  such 
individuals  that  our  knowledge  begins,  and  the  whole  process 
of  generalisation  has  as  its  object  and  end  the  understanding 
of  them.  It  will,  however,  only  allow  us  to  have  knowledge  of 
them  with  regard  to  those  features  which  they  possess  in 
common  with  other  individuals,  leaving  us  still  in  ignorance 
as  to  what  it  is  that  constitutes  them  as  individuals,  or  as 
differentiated  from  other  concrete  substances ;  for  the 
individual,  while  undifferentiated  in  itself,  is  yet  distinguished 
from  others,  as  S.  Thomas  says.1  If  what  has  been  said 
about  the  essential  unity  of  the  atom  and  molecule  be  true, 
•these  bodies,  at  least,  when  taken  singly,  will  be  true 
individuals  ;  even  if  we  are  obliged  to  deny  or  doubt  the 
individuality  of  larger  masses  of  inanimate  matter  ;2  and  we 
wish  to  discover  what  it  is  precisely  which  is  the  root  of  their 
unity  and  of  their  distinction  from  other  bodies  of  the  same 
nature  as  themselves.  This  question  as  to  the  root  of 
numerical  unity  is  known  as  the  problem  of  the  principle  of 
individuation,  and  is  one  of  the  most  recalcitrant  and  obscure 
of  the  many  difficult  problems  discussed  in  mathematical 
philosophy. 
The  history  of  the  consideration  of  this  problem  may  be 

1  Summa  Theol.,  Pars  I,  Q.  29,  a.  4. 

*  For  a  full  discussion  of  this  question  see  Nys,  Cosmologie,  Vol.  II, 
pp.  281-294. 

151 


152         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

said  to  begin  with  Aristotle  who  regarded  the  individual  as 
containing  reality  in  itself,  in  contrast  to  Plato,  who  looked 
upon  the  subsisting  Forms  as  constituting  reality.  The 
former  finds  in  the  individual  two  kinds  of  unity,  a  unity  of 
nature,  which  it  shares  with  other  individuals,  and  a  unity 
which  is  all  its  own.  The  first  is  specific,  and  the  second 
numerical,  unity.  Specific  unity  is,  in  his  view,  derived  from 
form,  since  form  is  that  which  makes  the  substance  to  be 
determinately  what  it  is.  What,  then,  is  it  which  is  the  source 
of  the  numerical  unity  of  individuation  ?  Few  passages,  and 
those  ambiguous,  can  be  cited  in  which  individuation  seems 
to  be  ascribed  to  form  ;x  while  there  are  numbers  in  which  it 
is  distinctly  attributed  to  matter.  So  he  says  :  '  The  whole 
thing,  such  and  such  a  form  in  this  flesh  and  these  bones,  is 
Callias  or  Socrates  ;  and  they  are  different  owing  to  their 
matter  (for  this  is  different),  but  the  same  in  species,  for  the 
species  is  indivisible.'2  So  it  is  no  doubt  true  to  say  that 
Aristotle  thought  that  things  which  differ  numerically 
within  the  same  species  do  so  in  matter  only,  and  so  by  reason 
of  it. 

The  question  does  not  make  much  progress  till  we  come 
to  the  Arabian  philosophers  of  the  Middle  Ages  ;  though 
Boethius,  in  touching  on  it  incidentally,  seems  generally  to 
ascribe  individuation  to  accidents.  '  Ea  vero  qua  individua 
sunt  et  solo  numero  discrepunt,  solis  accidentibus  distant.'3 

Passing  then  to  the  Arabians,  Avicenna  (980-1037),  or 
rather  his  translator,  first  introduces  us  to  a  term  which  was 
to  become  famous  in  discussions  of  this  question,  by  using 
the  word  '  signatum  '  as  synonymous  with  '  determinate 
individual,'  which  thence  comes  to  be  applied  to  any  deter- 
minate reality.  Thus  we  hear  both  of  '  forma,'  and  of 
'  materia,'  '  signata.'  Since  a  nature,  he  contends,  is  not  of 
itself  individual,  the  relation  between  it  and  individuality  is 
an  accidental  one,  and  therefore  we  must  look  for  its  source 
not  in  essence,  but  among  the  accidents,  such  as  quantity, 
quality,  place,  and  time.    Nevertheless,  a  definite  theory  of 

1  Cf.  Met.,  I038bi4  ;    1071027-29  ;   Phys.,  412*6-9. 
1  Met.,  1034*5-8  ;  cf.  IOI6&32  ;    I035b27~3i  ;    1054334  ;    1074331-34  ; 
Phys.,  278*7^3. 

•  In  Isagogen  Porphyrii,  ed.  Brandt,  pp.  241,  9 ;  cf.  De  Trinitate,  I. 


THE   INDIVIDUAL  153 

individuation  is  not  worked  out  by  Avicenna,  though  his 
dicta  about  it  should  logically  lead  to  the  conclusion  that  its 
source  lies  in  matter  which  is  determined  by  spatial  dimen- 
sions. No  doubt  this  latent  conclusion  was  perceived  by  the 
penetrating  mind  of  S.  Thomas  :  who,  however,  was  also 
much  influenced  in  this  question  by  another  writer  of  the 
same  race — Averroes  (1126-1198).  According  to  Averroes, 
known  in  the  Middle  Ages  as  the  Commentator,  from  his 
exhaustive  commentaries  on  Aristotle,  matter  is  in  itself 
numerically  one,  since  being  undetermined,  it  cannot  be 
many.  Nevertheless,  it  is  divisible,  and  that  which  makes  it 
so  must  be  quantity,  i.e.  the  three  dimensions  of  the  con- 
tinuum. Hence  matter  must  be  conceived  as  carrying  with 
it,  not  this  or  that  three-dimensional  extension,  but  exten- 
sion in  general — '  unterminated  extension  or  dimensions.' 
So  first  matter  is  in  potency  to  a  determination  by  three 
dimensions  in  general,  which  potency  is  logically  prior  to  that 
which  it  has  for  being  determined  by  a  specific  form. 

The  theories  of  Avicenna  and  Averroes  seem  to  have  had  a 
predominant  influence  on  the  thought  of  S.  Thomas  (1224- 
1274) ;  which  vacillates  in  a  remarkable  fashion  between  their 
explanations.  He  never,  as  it  seems,  had  the  least  doubt 
with  regard  to  the  Aristotelean  theory  of  individuation  by 
means  of  matter  ;  but  he  hesitates  for  some  time  as  to  the 
way  in  which  this  general  theory  should  be  understood. 
After  accepting,  at  first,  the  expressions  and  theory  of 
Avicenna  that  the  principle  of  individuation  is  matter 
designated  by  determined  dimensions,1  he  abandons  it  in 
favour  of  the  Averroist  opinion  that  it  is  matter  affected  by 
unterminated  dimensions  which  is  this  principle.2  He  makes 
considerable  use  of  this  second  theory,  only  in  the  end  to 
throw  it  over  and  return  once  more  to  the  view  that  the 
dimensions  are  determined  ones.3 

The  reason  of  this  change  of  opinion  is  almost  certainly  to 
be  found  in  S.  Thomas'  keener  realisation  of  all  the  con- 
sequences which  flow  from  the  strict  acceptance  of  the 
doctrine  of  the  uniqueness  of  substantial  form  :   since  the 

1  De  ente  et  essentia,  Cap.  2. 

4  In  Boethium  de  Trinitate,  Q.  4,  A.  2,  et  ad  311m. 

*  e.g.  Quodlibet,  XL,  a.  6,  ad  2um. 


154         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

Averroist  theory  really  implies  some  real  priority  of  the 
unterminated  dimensions  to  substantial  form. 

A  few  words  must  be  added  with  respect  to  the  subsequent 
history  of  this  discussion  in  the  Schools,  though  it  is  impossible 
to  treat  it  fully,  or  to  examine  non-Scholastic  views  of 
individuation. 

Scotus  (i265(?)-i3o8)  held  that  the  source  of  individuation 
is  the  numerical  determination  of  the  form  and  matter  of  the 
compound,  by  which  they  become  this  form  and  this  matter. 
He  maintains,  further,  that  it  is  distinguished  from  the 
nature  of  the  thing  by  a  formal  distinction  a  parte  rei,  i.e.  it 
is  not  wholly  identified  as  a  reality  with  the  nature.  He 
says  it  is  the  'ultima  realitas  entis  '  ;x  and  though  not  sub- 
stantial form  is  yet  of  the  nature  of  a  formality  as  determin- 
ing the  thing  to  be  '  this.'  He  calls  it  '  hcecceitas  '  or 
'  thisness  '  ;  so  that  a  thing  is  this  by  its  thisness,  it  is  an 
individual  by  means  of  the  last  reality  of  its  being :  a 
conclusion  which  is  not  very  illuminating. 

Ockham  (c.  1300-1348),  and  the  Nominalists  generally, 
necessarily  regard  the  question  as  to  the  principle  of  individua- 
tion as  meaningless,  since  they  do  not  admit  as  realities 
independent  of  the  mind  any  universal  or  specific  natures, 
but  only  individual  things  or  phenomena.  Hence  the 
individual  is  distinct  of  itself,  and  not  multiplied  in  the 
species,  the  latter  being  either  a  mere  concept  or  a  group 
name. 

Suarez  (1548-1617)  considers,  in  opposition  to  Scotus, 
that  the  principle  of  individuation  can  only  be  logically  dis- 
tinguished from  the  individual  being.  Every  being,  even  an 
incomplete  one,  is  individual  of  itself,  by  reason  of  its  entity. 
He  is  particularly  determined  in  his  opposition  to  the 
Thomist  thesis  which  would  see  in  a  part  of  the  nature 
only,  viz.  matter  affected  by  quantity,  the  principle  of 
individuation.2 

It  is  essential  to  notice  that  in  this  enquiry  we  are  not 

1  Opus  Oxoniense,  II,  dist.  Ill,  Q.  2,  No.  15. 

*  Disp.  Metaph.,  V,  Sect.  3.  Cf.  Mahieu,  Francois  Suarez,  pp.  112  ff. 
The  greater  part  of  the  foregoing  account  of  the  history  of  this  problem 
is  derived  from  Fr.  Roland-Gosselin's  masterly  analysis  in  his  edition  of 
the  De  ente  et  essentia  ;  particularly  with  regard  to  S.  Thomas'  opinions. 


THE  INDIVIDUAL  155 

looking  for  the  proximate  cause  of  individuation,  but  its 
root  or  first  cause  ;  nor  yet  do  we  wish  to  discover  how 
individuals  are  to  be  distinguished  by  it,  how  we  recognise 
them  as  distinct  individuals,  but  how  they  are  distinguished 
from  one  another  in  themselves.1 

The  Thomist  school  all  answer  this  question  by  saying  that 
the  principle  is  matter  signed  or  sealed  by  quantity  :  which 
at  this  stage  we  may  take  as  meaning  matter  which  has  a 
relation  to  quantity — Wicksteed  describes  it  as  '  earmarked 
by  quantity  '2 — though  later  we  will  examine  this  phrase 
more  closely.  It  is  necessary  to  discuss  this  question  fairly 
fully  since  S.  Thomas'  view  on  this  subject  is  at  the  very 
heart  of  his  metaphysical  system,  to  such  an  extent  that  its 
abandonment  would  seem  to  involve  the  abandonment  of 
his  whole  conception  of  the  universe  ;  and  conversely  a  real 
grasp  of  it  will  greatly  help  to  an  understanding  of  the 
whole  of  his  philosophy.  We  have  already  had  occasion  to 
notice  that  the  theory  of  matter  and  form  is  a  particular 
case  of  the  Aristotelean  division  of  being  into  potency  and 
act — though  almost  certainly  not  a  derivative  of  it — and 
this  thesis  is  another  special  case  of  that  theory.  For  multi- 
plication implies  a  distinction,  and  so  a  restriction  or  limita- 
tion, which  limitation  implies,  in  its  turn,  some  imperfection 
or  potency  ;  from  which  it  follows  that  an  act  which  is  com- 
plete and  perfect  in  its  own  order,  both  as  a  substance  and  as 
a  species,  cannot  be  multiplied  in  that  order  ;  and  also  that  if 
any  form  or  act  is  multiplicable,  this  cannot  come  about 
from  the  form  or  act  itself  ;  since  this  in  itself  implies  no 
limitation.  The  multiplication  must  therefore  come  from 
potency  or  matter. 

To  prove  their  contention  that  the  principle  of  individu- 
ation must  be  matter  determined  by  quantity,  the  Thomists 
argue  in  the  first  place  that  no  other  principle  can  be  dis- 
covered which  will  satisfy  the  necessary  conditions,  viz.  to 
multiply  substantial  individuals  within  the  species  ;  since  in 
any  material  substance  we  can  distinguish  four,  and  only 

1  Cf.  Salmanticenses,  Cursus  Theol.,  Vol.  I,  Tract.  I,  Disp.  I,  Dub.  2, 
No.  45  f. 

'  The  Reactions  between  Dogma  and  Philosophy  (1926),  p.  368. 


156         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

four,  elements  :  matter,  form,  subsistence  (i.e.  that  by  which 
the  thing  is  put  in  the  category  of  substance,  and  made  self- 
supporting  or  existing  per  se,  or  on  its  own  account),  and 
existence.  The  last  two  cannot  possibly  be  the  principle  of 
individuation,  since  they  both  belong  to  the  existential 
order,  and  so  presuppose,  as  a  necessary  condition  of  their 
own  individuality,  an  individual  nature  already  constituted. 
The  reason  of  this  is  that  existence  being,  in  itself,  all  of  a 
kind,  must,  if  it  is  to  be  differentiated  and  made  individual 
at  all,  be  so  differentiated  by  something  other  than  itself, 
i.e.  by  nature.  Moreover,  we  are,  in  fact,  asking  how  we 
can  have  an  individual  nature,  so  that  the  question  is  con- 
cerned with  the  order  of  nature  or  essence,  not  existence. 
Neither  can  form  be  the  principle  we  are  looking  for,  since 
form  differentiates  things  specifically,  for  the  very  concep- 
tion of  form  implies  that  it  is  form  which  makes  a  thing  to  be 
of  a  determined  species  :  so  that  when  form  varies,  the 
species  varies.  Consequently,  matter,  as  the  only  remaining 
element  in  the  thing,  must  be  the  principle  of  individuation. 
Matter,  however,  does  not  seem  to  be  capable  of  filling  the 
role  required  of  it,  for  it  is,  as  we  have  seen,  altogether 
potential  and  undetermined  in  itself,  so  that  it  could  not 
determine,  or  differentiate,  anything  else.  If,  then,  it  is  to 
do  this,  it  must  be  in  some  way  determined.  Such  deter- 
mination as  is  required  evidently  cannot  come  to  it  from 
substantial  form,  since  we  are  looking  for  numerical,  not 
specific,  determination  :  while  the  very  word  '  numerical ' 
suggests  that  it  does  come  from  that  accident,  which  is  most 
closely  united  to  it,  and  which  is  numbered,  viz.  quantity ; 
which  is  also,  as  we  saw,  individual  of  itself  (cf.  p.  65).  In  so 
far,  then,  as  matter  has  a  relation  to  this  quantity  rather 
than  that,  it  can  be,  and  is,  the  principle  of  individuation. 

Again,1  if  we  look  at  the  question  directly  we  see  that  two 
things  are  required  for  the  principle  of  individuation  ;  first, 
that  it  should  be  an  intrinsic  substantial  principle  of  incom- 
municability  of  form ;  and,  second,  that  it  should  be  the 
principle  whereby  one  body  is  made  distinct  from  all  others. 
Now,  that  matter  is  an  intrinsic  substantial  principle  is  clear, 

1  For  the  following  argument  cf.  Summa  TheoL,  Pars  III,  Q.  77,  a.  2. 


THE   INDIVIDUAL  157 

and  moreover,  being  the  basic  and  primary  substratum  of. 
bodies  it  is  unable  to  be  received  in  anything  else  ;  from 
which  it  follows  that  any  form  which  is  received  in  it  will  like- 
wise be  unable  to  be  received  over  again,  and  so  will  be 
rendered  incommunicable  so  far  as  reception  in  a  subject  is 
concerned.  The  principle  of  distinction  from  others,  on  the 
other  hand,  is  not  matter,  since  this  is  in  itself  undiffer- 
entiated ;  while  the  source  of  differentiation  and  division  is 
extended  quantity,  for  a  thing  is  rendered  naturally  incapable 
of  existing  in  several  things  if  it  is  undivided  in  itself,  and 
divided  from  all  others.  It  is  clear,  moreover,  that  it  is 
extension  which  divides  substance,  and  so  is  a  kind  of 
individuating  principle,  inasmuch  as  forms  are  numerically 
differentiated  by  being  in  different  parts  of  matter.  That 
quantity  is  indeed,  in  this  way,  a  principle  of  individuation 
can  be  seen  in  the  order  of  pure  quantity,  inasmuch  as  we 
can  imagine  several  lines  of  the  same  species,  differing  only 
by  their  position  in  space  :  and  the  same  is  true  of  other 
geometrical  figures.  Such  difference  in  position,  however, 
belongs  to  quantity.  Hence  a  double  principle  of  individu- 
ation is  required,  matter  and  quantity,  or  matter  determined 
by  quantity.  From  this  we  can  see  the  way  in  which  the 
phrase  '  materia  signata  quantitate  '  ought  to  be  understood  : 
a  much  controverted  question. 

Sylvester  of  Ferrara  held  that  materia  signata  is  a  com- 
pound of  matter  and  the  quantity  which  actually  informs  it. 
This  idea  is  perfectly  clear  and  acceptable  if  we  consider  an 
existing  individual ;  which,  of  course,  has  a  particular 
quantity ;  but  it  is  not  satisfactory  if  we  consider  the 
individual  in  the  process  of  coming  into  existence,  and 
attempt  to  determine  how  it  came  to  be  individualised  ; 
since  the  matter  could  not  be  actually  informed  by  a  parti- 
cular quantity  until  it  had  already  received  a  substantial 
form.  Now,  it  is  precisely  with  the  individuation  of  this 
form  that  our  enquiry  is  concerned  ;  and  so  we  cannot  ascribe 
such  individuation  to  actually  informing  quantity,  since 
being  posterior  to  form  it  cannot  be,  in  the  same  order,  prior 
to  it,  and  so  cannot  make  the  matter  to  be  this  rather  than 
that,  and  thus  individuate  form. 


158         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

In  order  to  meet  this  and  other  difficulties  in  the  opinion 
of  Ferrariensis,  Cajetan  and  the  majority  of  Thomists  say 
that  materia  signata  must  be  explained  as  first  matter  which 
has  a  radical  requirement  for  this  quantity  rather  than  that : 
for  first  matter,  being  the  potential  principle  of  bodies, 
requires  quantity. 

First  matter  in  general  requires  quantity  in  general,  and 
so  this  or  that  determined  matter  requires  this  or  that  deter- 
mined quantity.  Hence  the  radical  requirement  for  a 
determined  quantity  is  considered  as  prior  to  the  coming  of 
substantial  form,  and  actual  quantity,  to  the  body.  This, 
perhaps,  lessens  the  difficulty,  but  does  not  clear  it  up  ;  for 
how  can  matter  which  is  altogether  undetermined  have  a 
determinate  requirement  ?  To  answer  this  an  appeal  is 
made  to  the  Aristotelean  principle  of  reciprocal  priority  of 
mutual  causes.1  According  to  this  principle,  causes,  which 
are  causes  of  one  another  are  in  different  genera  of  causality  ; 
and  in  this  case,  quantity,  being  an  accidental  form,  is  pos- 
terior to  substantial  form  in  the  genus  of  efficient  causality, 
but,  since  it  is  at  the  same  time  a  disposition  which  disposes 
matter  to  receive  this  form,  it  is  prior  to  it  in  the  genus  of 
material  disposing  causality.  So  the  matter  in  which 
the  new  form  is  about  to  appear,  being  disposed  to  receive 
this  form,  is  also  disposed  to  receive  the  quantity  which  goes 
along  with  it.  This  explanation,  however,  seems  only  to 
give  us  matter  with  a  requirement  for  some  quantity  within 
the  limits  of  the  quantities  which  are  suitable  to  the  form  in 
question,  as  e.g.  the  quantities  suitable  to  elephants  as 
opposed  to  those  suitable  to  mice.  Such  quantity,  it  is  plain, 
cannot  be  said  to  be  individually  determinate  ;  in  fact,  the 
very  idea  of  it  is  of  that  quantity  outside  whose  limits  we 
should  not  find  a  member  of  the  species,  and  within  whose 
limits  we  might  find  any  individual  of  it,  not  a  particular 
one.  Now,  as  we  have  seen,  quantity  essentially  consists  in.  a 
plurality  of  parts,  and  one  quantity  is  differentiated  from 
another,  and  is  this  quantity  as  opposed  to  that,  by  a  different 

1  Cf.  S.  Thomas  in  V  Metaph.,  Lect.  2  ;  de  Veritate,  Q.  28,  Arts.  7 
and  8.  John  of  S.  Thomas,  Cursus  Phil.  Phil.  Nat.,  P.  II,  Q.  1,  A.  7, 
and  Q.  9,  A.  4.  Salmanticenses  Cursus  Theologicus,  Tom.  I.  De  Principio 
Individuationis,  Disp.  I,  Dubium  5,  Sect.  3. 


THE  INDIVIDUAL  159 

order  of  parts  in  the  whole.    So,  in  a  homogeneous  body 
one  part  differs  from  another  by  its  position  in  the  whole 
body,  and  having  thus  once  acquired  an  individuality  it 
retains  it,  even  if  its  position  in  the  whole  be  changed.    If  we 
apply  this  idea  to  a  body  which  is  about  to  undergo  a  sub- 
stantial change,  we  see  that  at  the  instant  before  the  change 
it  has  a  determinate  order  of  parts,  and  occupies  a  deter- 
minate '  situs  '  or  position  with  respect'  to  all  the  other 
bodies  in  the  universe.    Then  comes  the  change,  and  the  new 
form  is  drawn  out  of  matter  under  the  action  of  the  agent, 
the  matter  having  been  so  modified  as  to  be  disposed  to 
receive  just  this  form  and  no  other,  among  such  predisposi- 
tions in  it  being  that  it  requires  to  occupy  a  definite  situs, 
viz.  that  of  the  corrupted  body.  Thus  the  new  body  also  has  a 
requirement  for  occupying  this  same  situs,  and  so  is  made 
individual.     Having  once  gained  such  individuality  it  can 
retain  it,  i.e.  it  can  remain  divided  from  every  other  body  by 
reason  of  its  actual  quantity  at  any  given  moment,  and 
remain  unable  to  be  subjected  in  any  other  by  reason  of  its 
matter.     Being  thus  an  individual,  if,  as  in  the  case  of  living 
things,  it  takes  up  new  matter  into  itself  and  grows,  thus 
altering  its  quantity,  it  does  not  thereby  lose  its  individual 
identity,  since  it  makes  the  new  matter  part  of  itself,  both 
specifically  and  individually,  by  a  continuous  process. 

If  this  theory  be  correct,  it  is  evidently  in  accord  with 
S.  Thomas'  requirement,  in  the  last  phase  of  his  thought  on 
this  question,  for  a  determinate  quantity  as  a  co-principle  of 
individuation  with  matter  ;  and  avoids  the  difficulty  which 
he  eventually  found  in  accepting  the  Averroist  theory  of 
matter  affected  by  unterminated  quantity,  viz.  that  such 
quantity  must  be  conceived  as  prior  to  substantial  form  in 
the  matter.  According  to  the  view  just  outlined,  there  is  no 
real  priority  of  quantity,  whether  determined  or  undeter- 
mined, to  form,  but  merely  a  requirement  in  the  matter  for 
the  occupation  of  a  determinate  situs  or  position,  owing  to 
the  fact  that  the  body  at  the  instant  of  corruption  actually 
occupied  that  situs.  Thus,  no  actual  quantity  remains 
through  the  change,  but  the  matter  has  been  predisposed  to 
receive  a  form  accompanied  by  a  determined  quantity.    The 


160         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

quantity  in  the  generated  substance  will  not  be  numerically 
the  same  as  that  in  the  corrupted  one,  since,  like  all  other 
accidents,  it  will  be  individuated  by  its  subject :  even 
though,  as  we  saw,  it  possesses  a  certain  distinction  and 
individuation  of  its  own.  Its  actual  dimensions,  qua  dimen- 
sions, remain  the  same,  but  they  are  now  the  dimensions  of 
the  body  B,  whereas  before  they  were  those  of  A.  The  fact, 
however,  that  they  are  the  same  ;  in  other  words,  that  the 
generated  body  occupies  the  same  situs  as  the  corrupted  one, 
and  that  the  matter  which  is  in  each  has  therefore  a  require- 
ment for  this  situs,  enables  us  to  say  that  this  matter 
remains  the  same  under  the  change.  '  This  '  matter,  which 
is  marked  out  as  '  this  '  by  the  requirement  for  a  definite 
position  and  quantity,  is  found  both  in  the  corrupted  and 
generated  body  :  a  state  of  affairs  which  seems  to  be 
demanded  by  our  common  way  of  talking  about  such 
changes,  as,  for  example,  this  wood  has  turned  into  this  ash  ; 
this  dead  body  is  the  body  of  such  and  such  a  man,  and  so  on.  1 

It  seems,  then,  that  there  can  be  no  doubt  that  matter  is 
the  principle  of  individuation,  since,  as  S.  Thomas  says  : 
'  Differentia  quce  ex  forma  procedit  inducit  diversitatem  speciei  ' 
{Contra  Gentiles,  Lib.  II,  Cap.  93),  which,  as  we  noticed 
before,  is  a  consequence  of  the  principle  that  act,  if  it  is  to  be 
limited  and  multiplied  must  be  so  limited  by  potency. 

Nevertheless,  certain  further  difficulties  arise  with  respect 
to  the  theory,  for  it  seems  that  if  first  matter  has  a  require- 
ment for  a  definite  quantity,  it  is  already  determined  to  a 
certain  extent,  or  actuated,  and  so  does  not  lose  all  its  actu- 
ation in  substantial  change,  in  contravention  of  what  we 
have  already  seen  is  necessarily  required  in  such  change. 
This,  however,  is  not  the  case,  for  just  as  first  matter  in 
general  is  not  a  capacity  for  receiving  all  forms  of  whatsoever 
kind,  but  only  material  ones,  so  that  it  is  determined  extrin- 
sically,  though  not  intrinsically,  similarly  '  this  '  matter  has  a 
great  deal  of  its  capacity  taken  away  from  it,  but  neverthe- 
less, what  remains  is  a  sheer  capacity,  not  any  positive  deter- 

1  This  theory  of  individuation,  in  so  far  as  it  attributes  an  important 
role  to  situs,  was  proposed  by  Fr.  Geny,  S.  J.,  Gregorianum,  April  1921,  pp. 
290  &,,  with  acknowledgements  to  the  Venetian  Province  of  the  Society. 


THE  INDIVIDUAL  161 

mination.  The  Scholastics  express  this  by  saying  that  it  has 
a  transcendental  relation  to  '  this  '  quantity,  i.e.  a  relation 
which  is  not  something  added  to  it,  but  is  its  very  self  ;  just 
as  matter  as  such  has  a  transcendental  relation  to  material 
form  as  such.  They  are  correlatives,  one  implying  the  other. 
The  matter  remains  purely  potential,  but  its  capacity  is 
limited  ;  as  in  the  case  of  two  vessels  of  different  sizes,  the 
smaller  one's  actual  content  would  be  less  than  that  of  the 
larger,  and  yet  both  may  be  equally  empty  ;  so,  in  the  case 
of  our  two  '  matters,'  both  may  be  equally  potential.  The 
matter  which  has  a  transcendental  relation  to  a  definite 
quantity  is  no  less  potential  than  matter  in  general,  but  there 
is  less  potentiality. 

Again,  it  might  seem  that  our  principle,  though  sufficient 
to  account  for  the  individual  distinction  of  two  bits  of 
inanimate  matter,  such  as  two  stones,  is  hardly  sufficient 
when  we  come  to  things  of  a  higher  order,  such  as  two  dogs, 
and  still  more  two  men.  This  difficulty  arises,  partly,  from 
the  fact  that  we  often  confuse  individuality  with  personality  ; 
but  we  can  hardly  insist  too  much  on  the  distinction  between 
them,  for  they  are,  in  fact,  at  the  opposite  ends  of  the  scale. 
Quite  apart  from  this  theory  of  individuation,  consideration 
shews,  as  we  shall  presently  see,  that  personality  is  the 
highest  and  most  perfect  thing  in  nature,  whereas  individu- 
ality is  almost  the  lowest.1  Further,  it  is  to  be  noticed  that 
by  individuality  we  mean  something  negative  :  this  thing  is 
not  that,  whereas,  as  we  ascend  in  the  scale  of  beings,  we  get, 
along  with  this  negative  character,  a  gradual  increase  of  a 
positive  character  as  the  things  become  more  and  more 
masters  of  themselves.  Such  self-mastery  is  in  proportion 
to  the  capacity  for  action  on  one's  own  account,  by  and  for 
oneself ;  in  other  words,  in  proportion  to  the  capacity  for 
immanent  action.  Now  a  plant  has  immanent  activities 
which  inanimate  things  have  not,  being  able  to  nourish  itself, 
grow,  and  reproduce  its  kind ;  animals  have  still  more  of 
such  immanent  activity,  for  they  direct  themselves  by  sense, 
and  men  most  of  all,  being  able  to  determine  their  own 

1  Cf.  Maritain,  Three  Reformers,  pp.  19  ff.,  where  this  distinction  is 
shown  at  length  with  many  of  its  applications. 


162         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

actions  both  by  sense  and  reason.  Thus  we  have  a  growing 
centralisation  and  self-control,  but  the  negative  division  from 
other  bodies  which  is  characteristic  of  individuality  remains 
the  same  :  and  we  can  legitimately  attribute  individuation 
to  matter,  while  recognising  a  growing  unification  in  the 
thing  itself  as  we  ascend  the  scale.1 

As  to  the  way  in  which  we  distinguish  one  individual  from 
another,  there  is  no  doubt  that  we  do  so  by  remarking  their 
different  accidental  characteristics,  such  as  position,  dimen- 
sions, shape,  colour,  etc.  ;  but  though  individuality  is  known 
to  us  by  means  of  these,  it  would  be  a  confusion  of  thought 
to  conclude  that  they  are  therefore  its  principle. 

If,  then,  the  principle  of  individuation  be  matter  affected 
by  a  transcendental  relation  to  a  determined  position,  it 
follows  that  material  substances  are  not  individuated 
absolutely  in  themselves,  but  in  relation  to  other  individuals, 
from  which  they  are  separated  ;  and  consequently  that  the 
principle  of  individuation,  though  intrinsic,  cannot  be,  as 
Suarez  maintains,  the  entity  of  the  thing  considered  abso- 
lutely. For,  if  this  were  so,  the  matter  of  one  thing,  con- 
sidered absolutely,  would  be  different  from  the  matter  of 
another,  and  so  would  not  be  common  matter.  This  would 
lead  us  to  conclude  that  any  two  substances  differ  essentially 
or  specifically  of  themselves.  Such  a  conclusion,  however, 
is  definitely  Nominalistic,  since  there  could,  in  this  case,  be 
nothing  universal  in  nature.  All  things  would  be  essentially 
different,  and  no  essential  concept  could  apply  to  several  of 
them.  On  the  other  hand,  if,  with  Scotus,  we  make  individu- 
ation something  added  to  the  nature  of  the  thing,  we  equiva- 
lently  assert  that  nature  without  such  addition  is  universal ; 
and  since  such  nature  is  found  in  individuals,  the  universal 
as  such  will  be  found  in  individuals.  This  view,  therefore, 
tends  towards  an  extreme  form  of  Realism.  In  saying  this 
our  intention  is  only  to  point  out  the  tendencies  which  seem 
to  be  implicit  in  the  views  of  these  two  great  thinkers,  not  to 
suggest  that  Suarez  was  a  Nominalist,  or  Scotus  an  advocate 
of  an  extreme  form  of  Realism.    In  any  case,  the  balance 

1  Cf.  M.  C.  D'Arcy,  S.J.,  Thomas  Aquinas,  pp.  148  ff.,  where  this 
difficulty  is  discussed  and  the  notion  of  immanence  emphasised. 


THE   INDIVIDUAL  163 

between  an  extreme  Realism  and  Nominalism  is  undoubtedly 
preserved  in  the  theory  of  S.  Thomas,  in  which  the  individual 
neither  absorbs  the  universal,  nor  is  absorbed  by  it.  Such  a 
moderate  realism  avoids  both  scepticism,  which  is  the  out- 
come of  Nominalism,  and  Monism,  from  which  extreme 
Realism  cannot  escape.  From  this  point  of  view,  therefore, 
this  thesis  may  be  said  to  be  a  postulate  of  the  Thomist 
theory  of  knowledge.  Indeed,  whether  we  look  at  the 
change  and  motion  in  the  material  world,  or  at  the  multipli- 
cation of  individuals  in  it,  or  at  our  knowledge  of  it,  the  facts 
force  us  to  say  that  the  only  intelligible  explanation  which 
can  be  given  of  them  is  that  this  world  and  all  things  in  it 
are  composed  of  two  elements,  one  of  which  is  actual  and 
the  other  potential,  and  of  which  the  latter  limits  the  former. 


CHAPTER  XIII 

SOME   GENERAL  CHARACTERISTICS   OF  THE   INANIMATE 
WORLD 

Physical    Laws    and    Theories — The    Formation    of    the    Material 
Universe — The  Infinity  and  Eternity  of  the  Universe. 

I.     Physical  Laws  and  Theories. 

To  enquire  into  the  ultimate  cause  of  the  universe  and  the 
method  of  its  production,  if  it  is  not  self-sufficient,  does  not 
come,  strictly  speaking,  within  the  scope  of  natural  philo- 
sophy, since  this  considers  the  material  world  in  itself.  At 
the  present  time,  however,  it  is  more  than  ever  evident  that 
it  is  subject  to  change,  and  has  not  always  been  in  the  state 
in  which  we  now  find  it.  Its  changes,  nevertheless,  must  be 
held  to  be  regulated  by  determinate  rules  ;  for  since  the 
Thomistic  theory  of  bodies  recognises  that  they  have  deter- 
minate natures,  they  must  also  have  determinate  modes  of 
action.  Such  modes  of  action  are  commonly  called  the  laws 
of  nature.  It  is  clear  that  such  laws  have  a  certain  necessity, 
since  they  are  consequents  of  the  natures  of  the  bodies  ;  but 
this  necessity  is  said  to  be  '  hypothetical ' ;  i.e.  dependent 
on  the  fulfilment  of  some  condition  ;  the  condition  in  this 
case  being  that  the  circumstances  remain  the  same,  and  that 
no  disturbing  influence  comes  into  the  system  of  inanimate 
nature  from  without.  If  this  condition  be  fufilled,  bodies 
will  always  act  in  a  certain  determinate  fashion  which  follows 
from  their  nature.  We  may  not,  however,  be  able  to  formu- 
late these  laws  adequately,  and  any  formulation  of  them  will 
naturally  be  bound  up  with  the  way  in  which  the  world  is 
regarded  by  physical  science  at  any  particular  epoch,  and  so 
with  physical  theories,  the  discussion  of  the  character  and 
value  of  which  belongs  properly  to  Epistemology,  or  the 
theory  of  knowledge.    It  may  not,  at  the  same  time,  be  out 

164 


CHARACTERISTICS  OF  INANIMATE  WORLD    165 

of  place  to  remark  here  that  some  writers  now  regard  these 
theories  as  having  only  a  phenomenal  value,  with  little  or 
no  connection  with  the  realities  which  may  or  may  not  underlie 
them  :  while  others  take  them  simply  at  their  face  value, 
and  transport  them  bodily  into  natural  philosophy.  In  this 
latter  view,  atoms,  electrons,  protons,  waves,  the  ether,  etc., 
are  treated  as  substances  on  the  same  terms  as  bodies  which 
fall  under  direct  sensible  observation.  This  view  seems  hardly 
tenable,  and  in  any  case  is  not  necessitated  by  the  notions  of 
the  physicists  themselves,  who  certainly  regard  sub-atomic 
elements  as  being  of  a  different  character  to  gross  matter. 
The  other  extreme  seems  also  to  be  inadmissible,  inasmuch 
as  the  theories  are  founded  on  quantitative  examination  of 
the  material  world,  and  therefore  cannot  be  wholly  uncon- 
nected with  the  material  reality  of  which  it  is  composed. 
From  this  it  is  clear  that  philosophy  cannot  ignore  physical 
theory,  nor  yet  regard  it  as  expressed  in  the  same  language 
as  that  which  it  uses  itself.  To  what  extent  physical 
theories  are  intended  to,  or  in  fact  do,  represent  ontological 
realities,  is  one  which  must  be  left  over  for  more  detailed 
consideration  at  a  later  stage. 

II.     The  Formation  of  the  Material  Universe. 

Since  the  changes  which  occur  within  the  material 
universe  come  within  the  limits  of  the  subject  matter  of 
natural  philosophy,  it  is  within  its  scope  to  examine  them, 
and  so  to  consider  the  whole  system  of  such  changes,  or  the 
world-process  in  general.  In  such  an  examination  it  will 
necessarily  be  directed  by  rational  or  metaphysical  principles, 
such  as  the  principle  of  finality,  which,  though  it  is  only 
in  metaphysics  that  they  are  demonstrated  to  be  absolutely 
general  ones,  applying  to  all  being,  can  yet  be  legitimately 
employed  here,  since  natural  philosophy  has  established 
their  validity  as  applied  to  bodies,  as  in  the  case  of  the 
principle  of  finality,  by  showing  that  bodies  have  determined 
natures.  Its  function  will  consequently  be  rather  negative 
than  positive,  in  so  far  as  it  will  endeavour  to  see  whether 
the  views  put  forward  by  natural  science  are  consonant  with 
reason  or  not. 


166         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

The  current  theory  with  regard  to  the  formation  of  the 
material  universe  is,  as  is  well  known,  the  following  : 

It  is  supposed  that  the  material  universe  at  first  existed  as  a 
uniformly  distributed  gas,  which,  supposing  the  total  amount 
of  matter  to  have  remained  constant,  and  calculating  on  the 
basis  of  the  amount  of  matter  now  existing,  must  have  been 
extremely  tenuous.  The  first  stage  in  the  growth  of  the 
universe  would  be  the  condensation  of  this  gas  into  giant 
nebulae,  not  stars,  as  Newton  conjectured.  Such  condensa- 
tions must  have  been  started  by  some  disturbance  in  the 
primeval  gas,  and  unless  this  motion  were  directed  exactly 
towards  the  centre  of  the  condensation  it  would  cause  it  to 
spin.  As  the  gas  is  contracting  this  spin  will  increase  in  pro- 
portion as  it  does  so,  and  the  result  of  the  process  will  be 
nebulae  rotating  at  different  rates.  This  is,  in  fact,  observed, 
viz.  that  the  nebulae  are  so  rotating.  A  nebula  which  was 
not  rotating  would  assume  a  spherical  shape  under  the  force 
of  its  own  gravitation,  but  rotation  will  cause  it  to  be  flat- 
tened at  the  poles  and  broadened  at  the  equator  until  it 
reaches  the  limit  of  such  flattening,  which  is  not  a  plane 
surface,  but  a  figure  of  the  shape  of  a  double  convex  lens. 
After  this  point,  since  flattening  cannot  proceed  any  further, 
the  nebula  will  begin  to  eject  matter  from  its  sharp  equa- 
torial edge,  and  a  thin  layer  of  gas  will  be  formed  in  the 
equatorial  plane.  Any  disturbance  in  this  mass  will  cause 
condensations  in  it,  of  which  the  larger  ones  only  survive. 
When  the  weights  of  the  smallest  condensations  which  could 
form  and  be  permanent  are  calculated  it  is  found  that  most 
of  them  are  comparable  with  that  of  the  sun.  For  this 
reason,  and  others,  therefore,  it  is  considered  that  this  is  the 
actual  process  by  which  the  stars  (of  which,  of  course,  our 
sun  is  one)  were  formed.  Thus  the  sun  and  all  the  stars  will 
have  been  born  out  of  rotating  nebulae.  The  galactic  system 
(the  Milky  Way)  is  supposed  to  have  been  a  rotating  nebula 
which  has  gradually  condensed  into  the  Galaxy  which  we 
now  observe,  and  in  which  our  solar  system  is  situated. 

Turning  now  to  the  formation  of  the  Solar  System,  we  see 
that  according  to  the  foregoing  theory  it  will  have  begun 
with  the  sun  as  a  condensation  of  the  gas  of  the  galactic 


CHARACTERISTICS  OF  INANIMATE  WORLD   167 

nebula,  which  condensation  will  be  in  rotation  since  its 
parent  was  rotating.  The  first  serious  scientific  attempt  to 
account  for  the  formation  of  the  Solar  System  in  its  present 
form  was  that  put  forward  by  Laplace  in  1796.  He  suggested 
the  idea  that  the  system  was  originally  a  nebula  in  rotation 
which  would  gradually  shrink,  and  its  shrinkage  making  it 
rotate  more  and  more  quickly,  he  showed  that  it  would 
flatten  out  and  emit  matter  in  its  equatorial  plane  in  the  way 
described  above  with  regard  to  the  formation  of  the  stars. 
Thus  the  planets  would  be  left  behind  by  the  main  mass 
(the  Sun)  as  this  shrank  continually.  This  view  was  accepted 
for  nearly  a  century,  but  has  now  been  abandoned,  for, 
according  to  the  theory  the  Sun  broke  up  and  produced  the 
planets  owing  to  its  excessive  rotation.  This,  however,  could 
not  have  been  the  cause  of  their  production,  since  it  is  now 
known  that  a  star  which  rotates  too  fast  does  not  form  a 
system  similar  to  the  Solar  System,  but  bursts  into  pieces 
of  nearly  equal  size,  a  result  which  is  observed  in  binary 
and  multiple  stellar  systems.  Moreover,  on  calculating  the 
angular  momentum  of  the  primeval  sun,  it  is  found  that  it 
could  not  have  been  sufficient  to  make  it  break  up  at  all ; 
and,  lastly,  the  mathematics  of  condensations  shows  that 
though  Laplace's  nebular  hypothesis  would  hold  good  with 
respect  to  vast  masses,  such  as  the  giant  nebula?,  it  cannot 
account  for  the  formation  of  small  bodies  such  as  planets, 
since  the  gas  left  behind  by  the  rotatory  motion  of  the 
Sun  would  be  too  tenuous  to  condense,  it  would  simply  be 
dissipated.  Thus  it  appears  that  though,  roughly  speaking, 
Laplace's  hypothesis  is  applicable  to  the  birth  of  suns  from 
the  original  nebula,  it  cannot  account  for  the  birth  of  planets 
from  the  Sun. 

Since  there  is  no  known  method  by  which  a  single  star 
could  give  rise  to  a  planetary  system,  the  theory  is  put  for- 
ward that  the  Solar  System  arose  through  the  approach  of 
another  star  to  the  Sun  while  the  latter  was  still  in  a  gaseous 
state.  This  is  known  as  the  tidal  theory,  which  suggests 
that  some  two  thousand  million  years  ago  a  second  star 
approached  near  enough  to  the  Sun  to  raise  in  it  an  enormous 
tide  of  the  nature  of  an  arm  of  gas  drawn  out  from  the  Sun's 


168         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

matter.  This  arm  would  be  of  sufficient  density  to  allow 
condensations  to  form  within  it,  the  larger  of  which  conden- 
sations became  the  planets.  These  will  follow  a  somewhat 
irregular  orbit  round  the  Sun,  in  the  course  of  which  they 
may  approach  near  enough  to  it  for  matter  to  be  drawn  out  of 
them  in  the  same  way  as  they  themselves  were  drawn  from 
the  Sun  ;  and  in  this  way  the  production  of  their  satellites 
is  accounted  for.  This  idea  is  confirmed  by  the  fact  that  the 
orbital  planes  of  the  planets  are  different  from  the  equatorial 
plane  of  the  Sun,  a  fact  which  is  unaccountable  on  Laplace's 
theory,  but  which  fits  in  well  with  the  notion  that  matter 
was  drawn  out  of  the  Sun  by  a  passing  star,  which  was  not 
in  the  plane  of  the  Sun's  equator. 

Now,  it  is  clearly  not  the  business  of  philosophy  to  decide 
what  degree  of  probability  attaches  to  these  theories  from 
the  scientific  point  of  view  :  this  is  determined  by  the  extent 
to  which  they  cover  the  known  facts,  and  the  simplicity  of 
the  picture  which  they  give.  Philosophy  can  only  say 
whether,  if  they  are  taken  to  represent  what  really  occurred 
in  the  past,  they  involve  any  elements  which  are  repugnant 
to  reason.  Now  it  is  clear  that  they  all  presuppose  that  the 
evolution  of  the  material  universe  came  about,  not  at  random, 
but  in  obedience  to  the  natures  of  the  bodies  considered, 
which  all  have  their  peculiar  properties  and  laws  ;  though 
some  laws  are  common  to  them  all — such  as  gravitation — 
and  others  to  large  classes — such  as  the  laws  governing  the 
condensation  of  gases.  No  account  is  given  of  the  origination 
of  the  primeval  nebula,  or  of  the  first  movements  in  it  which 
caused  rotation,  etc.  So,  no  objection  can  be  taken  to  the 
theories  on  the  ground  that  they  violate  the  principle  of 
causality  ;  and  since  they  all  recognise  determinate  charac- 
ters and  laws  in  natural  bodies,  they  do  not  violate  the 
principle  of  finality.  Hence,  from  no  point  of  view  can  it  be 
said  that  they  are  irrational ;  and  it  is  clear  that  since  the 
primeval  gas  is  supposed  to  have  had  a  definite  constitution, 
it  would  contain  virtually  the  developments  and  evolution 
which  followed  from  it. 

From  a  scientific  point  of  view  the  general  theory  of  the 
way  in  which  the  stars  were  produced  enjoys,  at  least,  a  high 


CHARACTERISTICS  OF  INANIMATE  WORLD   169 

degree  of  probability  ;  though  it  should  be  recognised  that 
all  we  can  affirm  positively  is  that  the  observations  show 
that  the  known  phenomena  are  such  as  they  would  have 
been  if  the  theory  represents  the  actual  events.  The 
universe  looks  as  if  it  had  been  formed  in  this  way. 

III.     Is  the  Universe  Finite  or  Infinite  in  Extent,  and  in 

Duration  ? 

(a)  The  first  question  has  already  been  answered  implicitly, 
since  we  have  seen  that  an  absolutely  infinite  quantity, 
whether  discrete  or  continuous,  is  an  impossibility.  It  is 
thus  clear  that  since  a  universe  which  was  actually  infinite 
in  extent  would  involve  the  actuality  of  both  these  infinities, 
it  is  therefore  impossible. 

(b)  The  second  question  does  not  admit  of  so  definite  an 
answer.  It  might  be  thought,  at  first  sight,  that  we  could 
rule  out  an  infinite  duration  of  the  world  on  the  same 
grounds  as  we  do  its  infinite  extent ;  but  it  is  clear  that  if 
we  cannot  exclude  such  a  possibility  we  can  then  ask 
whether  it  is  a  fact  that  it  has  had  an  infinite  duration. 

Let  us  consider  first  the  possibility  of  an  infinite  duration 
of  the  world.  If  the  universe  were  unproduced  by  any  cause 
it  would  clearly  have  such  a  duration,  since  it  exists  now, 
and  a  thing  cannot  bring  itself  into  existence.  Hence,  we 
should  have  answered  both  our  questions — as  to  possi- 
bility and  fact — affirmatively  ;  saying  that  it  is,  and  so 
obviously  can  be,  eternal.  If,  however,  the  world  has  been 
brought  into  existence,  does  it  follow  that  it  had  a  beginning 
in  time  ?  As  is  well  known,  S.  Thomas  startled  his  contem- 
poraries by  maintaining  that  reason  was  unable  to  prove  the 
necessity  of  such  a  beginning  in  time,  even  though  the  world 
was  acknowledged  to  have  been  created  by  God.  This 
assertion  depends  on  the  statement  that  causal  priority  does 
not  necessarily  involve  a  priority  of  time  ;  and,  in  fact,  in 
production  from  nothing  no  priority  of  time  can  be  involved, 
since  time  only  begins  with  the  production  of  the  world. 
There  cannot  be  a  moment  before  the  first.  The  universe 
itself  which  is  made  is  also  not  incompatible  with  infinite 
duration,  since  it  is  what  it  is  by  reason  of  its  nature,  which 


170         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

is  quite  independent  of  time  ;  and  this  holds  good  whether 
we  consider  a  single  static  thing  or  a  whole  series  of  successive 
ones,  for  in  the  first  case  the  single  being,  in  the  second  the 
whole  series,  would  endure  from  all  eternity.1 

If,  then,  we  cannot  exclude  the  possibility  of  the  infinite 
duration  of  the  world  in  the  past,  we  can  only  weigh  the 
probabilities  for  and  against  such  an  infinite  duration  having 
been  the  fact ;  and  all  Scholastics,  together  with  most 
theists,  think  that  the  weight  of  probability  is  on  the  side  of  a 
finite  duration  of  the  material  world,  both  in  the  past  and  in 
the  future.  They  argue  that  since  everything  of  which  we 
have  any  knowledge  had  a  beginning,  it  is  natural  to  con- 
clude that  the  world  as  a  whole  also  had  a  temporal  beginning. 
They  appeal,  further,  to  the  law  of  entropy,  according  to 
which  the  energy  of  the  world  is  tending  towards  a  state  of 
equilibrium,  and  consequently  since  this  state  of  equilibrium 
has  not  yet  been  reached,  the  process  cannot  have  been 
going  on  for  ever,  since  all  that  is  required  in  order  to  reach 
it  is  that  the  process  should  go  on  long  enough,  a  condition 
which  would  evidently  be  satisfied  in  an  infinite  time. 
Hence,  in  the  past,  there  must  have  been  a  beginning  of  this 
process,  when  the  available  energy  was  at  its  maximum  ; 
and  in  the  future  there  must  come  a  time  when  a  state  of 
energy  equilibrium  will  be  reached,  and  when  the  world  will 
cease  to  be  in  the  state  in  which  it  is  now. 

Further,  on  the  supposition  that  energy  is  liberated  and 
made  available  by  the  '  annihilation  '  of  matter,  as  is  sug- 
gested by  many  scientists,  it  will  follow  that  if  the  law  of 
entropy  holds  good,  and  the  material  of  the  universe  is  finite, 
there  will  be  a  definite  limit,  however  remote,  to  the  process 
of  the  liberation  of  energy,  and  consequently  there  must 
come  a  time  when  all  the  matter  in  the  universe  will  have 
been  annihilated.  Similarly,  in  the  past,  if  we  were  to  go 
back  to  infinity,  we  should  have  to  suppose  that  the  matter 
in  the  universe  was  infinite  in  weight,  a  supposition  which  is 
said  to  be  impossible  on  physical  grounds.2    In  accordance 

1  Cf.  Summa  Theologica,  Pars  I,  Q.  46,  Arts.  1  and  2  ;  Contra  Gentiles, 
Lib.  II,  Cap.  31-38  ;   Opusculum  De  Eternitate  Mundi. 

2  Jeans,  The  Universe  Around  Us,  Ch.  VI. 


CHARACTERISTICS  OF  INANIMATE  WORLD   171 

with  these  ideas  Sir  James  Jeans  says  :  '  the  present  matter 
of  the  universe  cannot  have  existed  for  ever  :  indeed,  we 
can  probably  assign  an  upper  limit  to  its  age  of,  say,  some 
such  round  number  as  200  million  million  years.'1 

It  is  clear  that  these  arguments  are  not  absolutely  demon- 
strative, both  because  they  do  not  show  that  there  is  a  con- 
tradiction in  the  supposition  that  the  world  has  had  an 
infinite  duration,  and  because  they  only  possess  the  same 
degree  of  probability  as  attaches  to  the  physical  theories  on 
which  they  are  founded.  From  this  point  of  view  the  argu- 
ment which  concludes  from  entropy  that  the  world  will  not 
always  remain  in  the  state  in  which  it  now  is,  seems  more 
certain  than  that  which  asserts  that  the  matter  of  the 
present  universe  will  come  to  an  end.  What  their  scientific 
value  is  can  only  be  estimated  by  physicists,  philosophy 
being  able  to  point  out  only  that,  however  highly  they  may 
be  esteemed  in  this  way,  they  are  not  demonstrative  ;  and 
that  in  itself  the  hypothesis  of  an  eternally  existing  material 
universe  does  not  involve  any  contradiction  or  absurdity. 

It  may  be  well  to  add,  in  conclusion,  that  to  speak  of  the 
world  beginning  '  in  time  '  is  clearly  an  inexact  phrase,  for  it 
is  impossible  that  there  should  have  been  any  time  before 
the  world  was,  time  being  the  measure  of  the  motion  of 
mutable  being,  which  therefore  began,  if  it  began  at  all,  with 
the  first  of  mutable  things.  We  can  only  speak  of  creation  in 
time  in  the  same  way  as  we  might  speak  of  the  source  of  a 
river  being  in  it. 

Conclusion. 

With  these  considerations  as  to  the  beginning  and  end  of 
the  material  universe  the  Cosmological  section  of  philosophy 
closes  ;  and  we  have  next  to  examine  a  special  class  of  beings 
which  are  found  in  it,  viz.  animate  ones,  the  discussions  with 
regard  to  which  form  the  second  part  of  Natural  Philosophy, 
which  is  commonly  called  by  the  Scholastics  Psychology. 

1  Op.  cit.,  p.  327. 


THE  PHILOSOPHY   OF  NATURE 
Part  II.— THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  ANIMATE  NATURE 

INTRODUCTION 

The  investigation  into  the  nature  of  living  beings  is  held  by 
the  Scholastics  to  be  a  part  of  Natural  Philosophy.  This 
fact  is  of  considerable  importance,  since  to  overlook  it  would 
result  in  a  fatal  confusion  of  this  study  with  what  is  now 
generally  known  as  Psychology.  The  latter  is,  in  fact,  an 
entirely  different  science  ;  but  the  name  Psychology  was 
originally  applied  to  the  philosophical  examination  of  the 
animate  world,  and  for  the  last  two  hundred  years  the 
Scholastics  have  used  it  in  this  sense,  and  so  as  the  name  of 
that  part  of  philosophy  which  we  are  now  beginning  to  con- 
sider. Philosophy,  as  we  saw,  deals  with  the  very  natures  of 
things,  and  is  concerned  with  their  actions  and  behaviour, 
only  in  so  far  as  these  give  us  insight  into  their  natures.  The 
recently  constituted  science  of  Psychology,  on  the  contrary, 
is  interested  to  discover  the  way  in  which  living  things,  and 
particularly  human  beings,  act,  and  to  establish,  if  it  can, 
the  laws  which  regulate  their  conduct  and  behaviour.  The 
distinction,  therefore,  between  Scholastic  and  modern  Psy- 
chology is  similar  to  that  which  we  have  already  noticed 
between  Cosmology  and  Physics.  Cosmology  tries  to  deter- 
mine the  inner  nature  of  material  things,  while  Physics  is 
concerned  with  the  laws  of  their  action  ;  so  that  the  former 
discusses  the  very  essence  and  reality  of  motion,  for  example, 
while  the  latter  lays  down  its  laws,  or  the  ways  in  which  it 
is  observed  to  occur.  Modern  psychology  is  therefore  an 
experimental  and  natural  science,  while  Scholastic  psychology 
is  a  rational  and  philosophical  one,  dealing  with  the  being  of 
living  things.  If  this  distinction  be  borne  in  mind  from  the 
start  it  will  prevent  any  false  expectations  being  entertained 

i73 


174         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

as  to  the  kind  of  truths  which  may  be  hoped  to  be  discovered 
by  means  of  Scholastic  psychology,  as  it  would  be  idle  to 
look  for  explanations  of  particular  human  actions  in  a 
science  which  sets  out  to  explain  the  nature  of  man  in 
general,  or  to  seek  for  a  discussion  of  abnormalities  in  one 
which  professedly  deals  with  the  normal.  So  our  study  will 
deal  with  the  nature  of  man  and  other  living  things  and  with 
their  powers,  but  will  not  attempt  to  investigate  in  detail  all 
their  particular  actions  and  behaviour,  especially  abnormal 
ones.  The  distinction,  moreover,  takes  the  sting  out  of  the 
objections  made  to  rational  psychology  which  assert  that  it 
deals  exclusively  with  unobservable  entities  such  as  the 
intellect  or  senses  ;  for  by  '  unobservable  '  is  meant  that 
these  realities  cannot  be  known  experimentally  in  the 
laboratory,  and  rational  psychology  does  not  profess  to  be 
an  experimental  science.  At  the  back  of  such  objections 
there  is  always,  in  fact,  present  the  conviction  or  prejudice 
that  nothing  can  be  known  which  cannot  be  so  experimentally 
observed  ;  but  this  is  a  prejudice  which  concerns  the  theory  of 
knowledge  in  general  (it  is,  in  fact,  what  is  known  as  Nomin- 
alism), and  has  no  greater  bearing  on  psychology  than  on 
any  other  philosophical  study.  The  discussion  of  it,  there- 
fore, would  be  evidently  out  of  place  here,  and  we  must  con- 
tinue to  trust  to  the  common-sense  belief  that  reason  can 
give  us  knowledge  which  is  additional  to  that  which  we  can 
derive  from  sensible  observation.  If  anyone  should  feel  any 
qualms  about  trusting  to  the  powers  of  the  reason  before  he 
has  examined  them,  perhaps  the  consideration  that  the 
proposition,  '  nothing  can  be  known  but  that  which  can  be 
observed  experimentally,'  is  itself  not  open  to  experimental 
verification — and  therefore  on  this  hypothesis  unknowable — 
may  be  sufficient  to  allay  them,  at  least  provisionally. 

That  rational  and  experimental  psychology  are  specifically 
distinct  sciences  is  undoubtedly  genuine  Thomistic  doctrine, 
as  can  be  seen,  both  in  particular  passages  where  S.  Thomas 
distinguishes  the  experimental  and  speculative  knowledge 
which  we  have  of  the  '  soul,'  asserting  their  difference,1  and 

1  Cf.  De  Veritate,  X,  8,  III.C.G.  46  ;  and  Barbado,  Actus  Primi 
Congressus  Thomistici,  p.  94. 


PHILOSOPHY   OF  ANIMATE  NATURE      175 

from  his  general  principles  for  the  distinction  of  the  sciences 
which  will  be  discussed  later.1 

If,  then,  it  be  granted  that  there  is  a  psychology  which  is  a 
rational  or  philosophical  science,  we  can  pass  to  a  considera- 
tion of  its  nature  more  in  detail. 

The  word  psychology  seems  to  have  been  introduced  by 
Melancthon,  and  means  literally  the  science  of  the  soul,  i.e. 
the  science  of  the  life-principle  ;  and  this  may  be  taken  to 
be  a  nominal  definition  of  it ;  which,  though  it  tells  us  what 
is  the  field  of  its  investigations,  is  yet  too  vague  to  enable  us 
to  distinguish  psychology  from  other  sciences  dealing  with 
life,  such  as  biology. 

Now  we  have  already  declared  that  the  psychology  which 
we  are  going  to  consider  is  to  be  a  part  of  philosophy,  so  that 
we  can  add  this  to  the  definition,  and  assert  that  psychology, 
in  our  sense,  is  the  philosophic  science  which  treats  of  the 
intrinsic  principle  of  life,  i.e.  of  vital  operations.  According 
to  this  view  of  it  psychology  will  deal  with  life  wherever  it  is 
found  :  in  man,  in  animals,  and  in  plants,  and  indeed  if  we 
wish  to  discover  the  nature  of  life  in  itself  it  would  be  absurd 
to  exclude  any  of  its  manifestations  from  our  scrutiny.  At 
the  same  time,  both  because  of  the  greater  facility  for  study- 
ing it,  and  because  of  its  higher  interest  for  us,  no  doubt  the 
life  of  man  will  occupy  the  foremost  place.  Hence  we  shall 
have  to  discuss  the  very  nature  of  life  in  general,  and  in  its 
various  grades  ;  to  do  which  we  shall  be  bound  to  consider 
the  nature  of  vital  operations,  since  it  is  only  by  observing 
the  actions  of  a  thing  that  we  can  arrive  at  any  knowledge 
of  its  nature.  In  doing  this  we  shall  make  use  of  our  common 
knowledge  of  vital  phenomena,  and  also  of  the  facts  which 
have  been  discovered  by  the  investigations  of  experimental 
science  in  this  field  ;  to  which  we  are  to  apply  those  rational 
principles  which  will  lead  us  to  the  further  knowledge  of  the 
primary  causes  which  produce  these  phenomena. 

From  these  remarks  can  be  seen  the  distinction  and 
relation  between  this  philosophic  science  and  the  experi- 
mental sciences  which  deal  with  living  bodies,  such  as 
Biology,   Physiology,   Morphology,   Anatomy,   and  so  on  ; 

x  Cf.  Epistemology ,  in  Vol.  II. 


176         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

for  the  first  of  these,  though  dealing  with  the  whole  range  of 
living  bodies,  yet  treats  them  only  from  the  point  of  view  of 
discovering  how  they  function,  not  of  what  they  are  in 
themselves,  while  the  others  are  concerned  merely  with 
some  particular  aspect  of  them.  But  though  distinct  they 
are  also  complementary,  for  rational  psychology  takes  into 
account  the  data  which  they  supply,  and  they,  in  their  turn, 
supplement  it  by  giving  us  knowledge  of  the  way  in  which 
living  things  function  and  behave.  This  behaviour  of  living 
things  in  the  various  circumstances  in  which  they  are  placed 
is  more  particularly  the  province  of  experimental  psy- 
chology, which  has  been  variously  defined  as  the  science  of 
psychical  states  and  processes,  or  knowledge  of  psychic 
phenomena.  So  Professor  Stout  says  :  '  Psychology  treats 
of  psychical  states  and  processes,  their  objects  as  such,  and 
the  conditions  of  their  occurrence,'1  Woodworth  says  it  is 
'  the  science  of  the  conscious  and  near-conscious  activities  of 
living  individuals.'2  Ward  asserts  that  'it  is  the  science  of 
individual  experience — understanding  by  experience,  not 
merely,  not  primarily,  cognition — but  also  and  above  all, 
conative  activity  or  behaviour  '  ;3  while  William  James  calls 
it  '  the  science  of  mental  life,  both  of  its  phenomena,  and  of 
their  conditions.'4  It  is  clear  that  all  such  definitions  limit 
the  province  of  psychology  to  the  study  of  the  observable 
manifestations  of  life,  excluding  that  of  the  very  nature  of 
life  itself  and  of  the  fundamental  causes  of  the  activities  of 
living  things.  The  discussion  of  these  would,  by  most 
modern  writers,  be  considered  to  be  metaphysical,  and  though 
Thomists  would  not  agree  to  rational  psychology  being 
reckoned  as  a  branch  of  metaphysics,  since  their  formal 
objects  are  different,  yet  they  are  at  one  with  the  non- 
Scholastic  writers  in  recognising  that  experimental  psy- 
chology is  a  natural  and  not  a  philosophical  science. 

That  rational  psychology  is  of  the  greatest  utility  is  evident 
if  we  consider  that  its  aim  is  to  understand  our  own  real 
nature.    Its  main  problem  is  the  relation  between  mind  and 

1  Stout,  Groundwork  of  Psychology,  p.  1. 

2  Woodworth,  Psychology,  p.  17  (cf.  p.  1). 

3  Ward,  Psychological  Principles,  p.  28. 

4  James,  Principles  of  Psychology,  Vol.  I,  p.  1. 


PHILOSOPHY  OF  ANIMATE  NATURE       177 

matter  ;  according  to  our  solution  of  which  will  follow  our 
view  as  to  the  intellectual,  moral  and  religious  capabilities 
of  man.  So  a  recent  writer  says  :  '  If  we  knew  just  how 
mind  affects  body,  and  how  body  affects  mind,  we  should 
have  the  clue  to  many  a  philosophical  riddle,  and  a  clue 
which  would  give  us  much  needed  guidance  not  only  in 
philosophy  but  in  many  a  region  of  practical,  moral,  and 
religious  activity  and  experience  in  which  our  generation  is 
groping  rather  blindly  and  is  longing  very  eagerly  for  more 
light.'1 

Our  discussion  will  naturally  fall  into  three  parts  dealing 
with  the  three  great  realms  of  living  things  :  plants,  animals, 
and  man.  This  must  be  prefaced  by  some  account  of  what 
we  mean  by  '  life  '  in  general,  and  completed  by  an  investi- 
gation of  the  origin  of.  and  connection  between,  living  things. 

1  Pratt,  Matter  and  Spirit,  p.  viii. 


DIVISION   I.     LIFE   IN  GENERAL 
CHAPTER  I 

VITAL   OPERATIONS 

Vital  Operations  in  General — Their  Distinctive  Characteristics — 
Different  Kinds  of  Vital  Operations — Vegetative,  Sensitive, 
Intellectual. 

Since  all  living  things  have  at  least  vegetative  life,  it  will  be 
convenient  to  include  under  this  head  not  only  those  general 
philosophical  conclusions  which  we  can  arrive  at  by  a  survey 
of  the  animate  world  as  a  whole,  but  the  more  particular  ones 
which  relate  to  the  life  of  plants. 

The  nature  of  life  in  itself  is  naturally  regarded  by  Aris- 
totle and  St.  Thomas  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  motion 
which  it  exhibits,  since,  as  we  saw,  they  regard  '  mobile 
being,'  or  things  subject  to  motion,  as  the  proper  object  of 
the  whole  of  Natural  Philosophy,  of  which  our  present  dis- 
cussion forms  part. 

Now  the  word  motion  can  be  taken  in  three  senses  :  (i)  In 
its  strictest  sense  it  signifies  local  motion  ;x  (2)  it  is  applied 
to  any  successive  mutation,  and  is  then  defined  as  the  act  of 
that  which  is  in  potency  as  such.2  This  meaning,  though 
wider  than  the  first,  yet  applies  to  motion  properly  so  called. 
(3)  A  still  wider  meaning  is  the  application  of  the  name  to 
any  change,  i.e.  any  transit  from  potency  to  act,  even  if  the 
change  be  instantaneous.  A  last  and  very  loose  sense  is 
when  the  word  motion  is  made  to  cover  any  kind  of  opera- 
tion, even  if  there  is  no  transit  from  potency  to  act,  so  long 
as  we  conceive  of  the  operation  as  if  there  were  such  a  transit. 

1  Cf.  Aristotle,  VIII  Physics,  Ch.  IX. 
8  Cf.  Cosmology,  Ch.  VIII,  p.  109. 

178 


VITAL  OPERATIONS  179 

This  last  meaning  applies  only  to  the  divine  operations.  In 
speaking  of  motion  in  connection  with  life,  we  do  not  limit  it 
to  any  one  of  these  senses,  but  it  is  taken  to  include  them  all, 
though  the  second  sense  is  more  particularly  applicable  to 
vital  motions. 

Section  I.     Vital  Operations  in  General. 

Observing,  then,  the  motions  of  living  things  of  all  kinds, 
Aristotle  notes  that  their  motion  has  a  common  characteristic 
and  peculiarity,  it  is  self-motion — they  are  automatic.  Even 
the  humblest  of  living  things  nourishes  itself  and  grows,  thus 
causing  itself  to  change  ;  and  this  power  is  found  nowhere  in 
the  inanimate  world.  Hence  he  defines  a  living  thing  as  one 
whose  natural  property  it  is  to  be  able  to  move  itself  j1  or 
rather  this  definition  implicit  in  Aristotle  is  made  explicit  by 
S.  Thomas.2 

It  should  be  noted  that  S.  Thomas  says  the  living  thing  is 
one  which  is  able  to  move  itself,  not  one  which  actually  does 
so  :  for  it  is  this  capacity  which  properly  constitutes  the 
essence  of  a  living  thing.  The  Scholastics  call  this  life  in  actu 
primo,  and  oppose  it  to  actual  self -movement,  or  vital  action, 
which  is  called  life  in  actu  secundo. 

We  may  notice  in  passing  that  since  to  move  oneself  is 
opposed  to  being  moved  by  another,  self-motion,  properly 
speaking,  consists  in  the  production  by  the  agent  of  an  opera- 
tion which  remains  in  the  agent,  and  so  is  immanent  action. 
However,  we  cannot  at  this  stage  be  quite  certain  that  the 
action  of  living  things  is  immanent,  i.e.  proceeding  from  an 
intrinsic  principle  to  an  intrinsic  term,  since  it  will  only  be  so 
if  they  are  essential  unities,  not  two  or  more  things  accident- 
ally joined  together  ;  and  this  has  not  yet  been  proved. 

It  is  clear  from  common  observation  that  there  are  three 
kinds  of  living  things  with  markedly  different  characteristics, 
viz.  plants,  animals,  and  man.  If,  as  we  shall  see  presently  is 
the  case,  these  three  kinds  are  distinguished  specifically  or 
essentially,  it  is  clear  that  the  word  life  will  apply  to  them  in 

1  VIII  Physics,  254t>i5.  Cf.  S.  Thomas,  Summa  Theol.,  I.i8,l  and  2  ; 
IaIIae.3j2,  ad  I. 

%  De  anima,  L.  II,  Lect.  I. 


180         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

senses  which  are  also  specifically  distinct ;  in  other  words,  it 
is  an  analogical  concept,  used  of  the  things  to  which  it  is 
applied  in  senses  which  are  simply  speaking  different,  though 
from  a  certain  point  of  view,  viz.  that  of  self-motion  in 
general,  the  same. 

If  it  be  true,  then,  that  the  essential  characteristic  of  living 
things  is  their  capacity  for  self-motion,  an  important 
corollary  follows,  viz.  that  they  are  necessarily  organic.  For 
all  motion,  as  we  have  seen,  involves  a  transit  from  potency 
to  act.  Now  it  is  clear  that  a  thing  cannot  be  both  in  potency 
and  act  in  the  same  respect  at  the  same  time  ;  in  other 
words,  it  cannot  be  capable  of  becoming  something,  and 
have,  at  the  same  time,  become  it ;  and  it  necessarily  follows 
that  if  we  have  a  thing  which  moves  itself  and  so  makes  itself 
pass  from  potency  to  act,  there  must  be  one  part  which  moves 
and  another  which  is  moved  ;  it  cannot,  as  a  whole,  both 
move  and  be  moved. x  The  parts,  then,  of  a  living  thing  must 
have  different  functions  and  different  activities,  which  will 
proceed  from  principles  of  action  which  differ,  at  least 
accidentally.2  Though  it  is  clear  from  this  that  if  there  are 
bodies  which  are  altogether  inorganic,  not  having  qualitative 
differences  in  their  different  parts,  they  will  be  inanimate  ;  it 
does  not  follow  that  all  inanimate  bodies  are  inorganic  in  this 
sense,  and  in  fact  we  have  seen  reason  to  believe  that  a 
rudimentary  organism  in  this—philosophical  sense  is  to  be 
found  in  the  inanimate  world  as  well  as  in  the  animate.3  It 
was,  nevertheless,  the  observed  structural  organisation  of 
living  things — both  in  the  single  cell,  as  well  as  in  more  com- 
plex bodies — which  so  struck  the  scientific  imagination  as  to 
make  the  name  organism  coextensive  in  biology  with  animate 
bodies,  while  inanimate  ones  are  known  as  inorganic.  Though 
this  distinction  may  not  be  an  absolutely  fundamental  one, 
yet  there  is  no  doubt  that  it  is  one  of  the  ways  in  which  living 
bodies  differ  from  inanimate  ones  ;  which  differences  it  will 
be  convenient  to  enumerate  at  this  stage. 

1  Cf.  I.C.G.,  c.  13  (Tertio  probat). 

*  Cf.  13th  Thomist  Thesis.    Revue  Thomisie,  1921,  pp.  276,  280. 

•  Cf.  Cosmology,  Ch.  XI,  pp.  148  fi. 


VITAL  OPERATIONS  181 

(a)  In  the  Physical  Order : 

i.  In  Internal  Structure.  As  we  have  just  noticed,  living 
things  are  composed  of  heterogeneous  parts,  either  cells  or 
combinations  of  cells,  forming  organs.  The  cell  consists  of 
two  parts,  the  cell-body  (protoplasm,  or  more  properly  cyto- 
plasm) and  a  nucleus  which  consists  of  a  modified  protoplasm 
(karyoplasm).  The  nucleus  is  spherical  and  denser  than  the 
rest  of  the  protoplasm.  Such  cells  are  found  only  in  living 
bodies  ;  inanimate  ones  not  presenting  such  differences  of 
internal  structure. 

2.  In  Shape.  Generally  speaking,  living  things  of  different 
species  have  a  determinate  shape,  the  varieties  of  species  and 
of  shape  being  very  numerous.  The  fixity  of  such  shape 
increases  as  we  ascend  in  the  scale  of  life,  the  lowest  forms 
being  able  to  vary  their  shape  considerably.  Such  deter- 
mination in  shape  is  not  found  in  the  inanimate  world  except 
in  the  case  of  crystalline  formations,  but  here  we  do  not  get 
the  immense  variety  of  shape  which  is  found  in  living  things, 
there  being  six,  and  only  six,  types. 

3.  In  Chemical.  Composition.  Living  things  are  com- 
posed of  many  and  almost  the  same  chemical  elements,  of 
which  a  number  are  not  found  in  inanimate  ones  in  nature  ; 
whereas  inanimate  bodies  have,  individually,  only  a  few 
chemical  constituents,  and  differ  from  one  another  in  the 
elements  of  which  they  are  composed.  Moreover,  the 
elements  found  in  living  things  are  constantly  changing, 
whereas  those  in  inanimate  ones  are  stable. 

(b)  In  their  Mode  of  Being  : 

1.  In  their  way  of  coming  into  being,  their  origin.  Living 
things  always  come  to  be  by  means  of  generation  by  another 
living  thing  :  whereas  chemical  action,  affinity,  and  valency, 
suffice  for  the  production  of  inanimate  ones. 

2.  In  Duration.  Living  things  need  nourishment  in  order 
that  they  may  endure  as  living  things  ;  and  even  so,  their 
powers  fail  and  they  die,  no  extrinsic  cause  being  needed  to 
destroy  them ;  whereas  inanimate  ones  endure  so  long  as 
they  are  not  corrupted  by  an  extrinsic  cause. 


182         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

(c)  In  their  Activities  and  Tendencies : 

It  is  here  that  we  see  the  most  marked,  and  from  the 
philosophical  point  of  view,  the  most  significant  distinction 
between  the  two  orders. 

1.  With  Regard  to  Nutrition  and  Growth.  Living  things  all 
feed  and  nourish  themselves,  so  preserving  their  life  and 
repairing  waste  tissues ;  while  they  also  add  to  their  own 
structure  intrinsically,  and  grow.  Inanimate  bodies,  on  the 
contrary,  if  they  increase  at  all  do  so  by  the  mere  juxtaposi- 
tion of  more  matter  to  themselves  from  without.  In  this 
connection  we  may  notice  that  all  living  protoplasm  breathes, 
taking  in  oxygen  and  giving  out  carbon-dioxide ;  it  also 
secretes  products  useful  to  the  organism  and  excretes  those 
which  are  useless  or  injurious  to  it.  Such  activities  are 
peculiar  to  living  things. 

2.  With  Regard  to  Reproduction.  All  living  things  increase 
by  reproduction,  giving  rise  to  successors,  similar  to  them- 
selves and  formed  out  of  their  own  substance.  The  most 
primitive  method  of  reproduction,  as  we  shall  see,  is  fission, 
by  which  the  living  thing  splits  up  into  two.  No  non-living 
things  behave  in  this  way. 

3.  With  Regard  to  the  Regularity  of  their  Actions.  The 
actions  of  the  living  thing  are  rhythmic,  as  breathing  and 
the  beating  of  the  heart.  Some  vital  rhythms  are  in  tune 
with  cosmic  changes  such  as  the  action  of  the  tides,  or  the 
changes  of  the  seasons.  This  last  is  very  obvious  in  plants. 
Though  it  is  clear  that  such  rhythm  is  not  absent  from  the 
inorganic  world,  yet  it  is  much  more  marked  in  the  organic, 
where  it  is  found  in  all  individuals,  and  not  merely  in  the 
mass  :  and  like  other  vital  actions  has  its  source  within  the 
living  thing  itself. 

These  observations  afford  us  strong  grounds  for  thinking 
that  living  things  differ  essentially  or  specifically  from 
inanimate  ones.  We  shall  have  occasion  to  return  to  this 
question  later,  since  it  is  evidently  one  of  great  importance 
for  philosophy,  being  another  example  of  the  problem  of  the 
one  and  the  many,  which,  as  we  saw,1  is  a  leading  issue  in 
natural  philosophy. 

1  Cf.  Cosmology,  p.  22. 


VITAL  OPERATIONS  183 

Meanwhile,  in  our  observations  of  the  animate  world  we 
have  noticed  that  there  are,  apparently,  three  different  kinds 
of  life  in  it,  viz.  that  of  plants,  of  animals,  and  of  man.  Can 
this  distinction  be  justified  philosophically  ? 

Section  II.     The  Different  Kinds  of  Vital  Operations. 

We  examine  these  operations  in  order  to  discover  what 
are  the  kinds,  or  grades,  of  life.  Now  the  Scholastics  are 
unanimous  in  asserting  that  there  are  three  main  grades  of 
life  which  include  all  others,  vegetative,  sensitive,  and  intel- 
lectual. To  establish  this  assertion  they  appeal  to  the 
following  consideration,1  among  others  : 

Since  it  is  the  essential  characteristic  of  vital  motion,  as 
we  have  seen,  to  be  always  from  within,  or  intrinsic,  it  will 
be  more  perfect,  or  more  fully  vital,  in  proportion  as  this 
characteristic  feature  is  more  completely  found  in  it.  Now, 
in  any  motion  we  can  consider  three  elements  :  the  execution 
of  the  motion,  its  determining  form  or  principle,  and  its 
object.  Consequently,  life  will  be  more  perfect,  and  so  allow 
us  to  distinguish  grades  of  perfection  in  it,  in  proportion  as 
one,  two,  or  all  three  of  these  elements  are  intrinsic  to  the 
living  thing.  Now,  observation  shows  us  that  in  plant  life 
only  the  first  of  these  elements  is  intrinsic,  for  though  plants 
undoubtedly  move  themselves,  and  so  execute  their  own 
motion  in  growth,  and  so  on,  yet,  since  they  have  no  know- 
ledge of  the  end  to  which  their  motion  is  directed,  it  is  clear 
that  both  this  end,  or  object,  and  the  principle  of  their 
motion  must  be  determined  for  them  by  nature,  and  cannot 
be  due  to  any"  activity  of  their  own.  If  we  now  turn  to  the 
animal  world,  we  see  that  the  animals,  like  the  plants, 
execute  their  own  motion,  but  they  also  do  so  with  some 
knowledge  of  what  it  will  bring  them,  and  it  is  this  knowledge 
which  is  the  principle  of  their  motion,  making  them  move  ; 
though  they  still  are  apparently  not  capable  of  determining 
the  end  to  which  they  will  move  for  themselves,  but  act 
according  to  the  instincts  or  natural  tendencies  of  their 
nature.-  Nevertheless,  it  is  clear  that  both  the  execution  of 
the  motion  and  the  principle  which  makes  them  move  are 

1  Cf.  Summa  Theologica,  1.18,3. 


184         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

intrinsic  to  the  animal  itself,  which,  by  knowledge,  receives 
into  itself,  in  a  certain  fashion,  the  object  towards  which  it 
moves  ;  and  thereby  causes  its  own  motion.  When  we  come 
to  man  we  observe  that  he,  like  other  animals,  moves  him- 
self and  knows  the  object  to  which  he  moves,  and  that  he 
further  determines  for  himself  what  this  object  shall  be, 
choosing  any  means  he  pleases  for  arriving  at  some  end  which 
he  has  in  view.  Hence  the  very  object  of  his  motion  itself  is 
constructed,  as  it  were,  by  man,  and  his  vital  motion  is 
wholly  intrinsic  and  so  in  a  high  degree  perfect.1  Evidently 
the  most  perfect  life  of  all  would  be  one  in  which  the"  vital 
motion  was  absolutely  intrinsic,  not  seeking  anything  out- 
side itself  at  all,  nor  receiving  the  form  of  its  motion  from 
without,  a  state  of  things  which  could  only  be  found  in  the 
case  of  an  infinite  being,  of  God. 

1  Cf.  also  Summa  Theologica,  1.78,1. 


CHAPTER  II 

THE   PRINCIPLE   OF  LIFE 

Is  it  One  Only  in  Each  Individual  ? — A  Difficulty — Opinions  on  the 
Divisibility  of  the  Life-principle — Answer  to  the  Question. 

There  can  be  no  doubt  that  such  vital  actions,  as  we  have 
just  been  examining,  must  proceed  from  some  vital  principle, 
since  they  are  clearly  accidental,  the  living  thing  acting  now 
in  one  way,  now  in  another.  Aristotle  and  S.  Thomas  call 
this  principle  of  life  the  soul,  and  if  what  we  have  just  said 
about  the  three  grades  of  life  be  true,  it  follows  that  there 
must  be  three  kinds  of  life-principle,  or  soul,  to  be  found 
among  living  things.  It  will  be  convenient  to  note  here  the 
definition  which  Aristotle  gives  of  the  soul,  though  we  cannot 
at  this  stage  claim  that  the  definition  has  been  fully  verified. 
According  to  him,  then,  the  soul  is  '  the  first  act  of  a  physical 
organic  body.'1  Now  first  act  is  substantial  form,  and  this 
definition  will  be  true  if  living  things  do  indeed  differ  essen- 
tially from  inanimate  ones,  since  it  is  clear  that  such  essential 
difference  must  proceed  from  the  principle  of  life  in  them, 
which  will  therefore  specify  them,  and  be  their  substantial 
form  ;  and,  secondly,  if  they  are  essential  unities,  so  that 
they  can  be  said  to  have  one,  and  only  one,  form  or  first  act. 
It  is  necessary,  then,  for  us  to  see  whether  in  fact  the  soul 
is  one  only  in  each  individual  living  thing ;  and  we  are 
immediately  confronted  with  a  fact  which  seems  incompat- 
ible with  its  being  so.  Just  as  when  we  were  discussing  the 
unity  of  substantial  form  in  chemical  compounds,  the  chief 
difficulty  in  the  way  of  our  asserting  it  was  that  the  mixture 
can  always  be  resolved  into  its  elements,  so  that  it  seemed 

1  HEPI  "I'TXHE.  B.l.4l2.b.5.   el  8f)  ti  KOivbv  iirl  wd<rrjs  \p vxqs  Set  \tyetv,  ( Irj  &.v 
evreXixeta.  i]  trpurr-q  (rui/xaros  (pvcriKou  dpyaviKOV. 

I85 


186         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

that  the  substantial  forms  of  the  elements  remained  as  such 
in  the  mixture,  so  here  we  find  that  in  the  lower  grades  of 
life  at  least,  and  to  a  certain  extent  in  the  higher,  a  living 
thing  can  be  divided  into  two  or  more  parts  without  losing 
its  life,  and  so  without  losing  its  substantial  form.  It  looks, 
therefore,  on  the  face  of  it,  as  if  there  were  many  principles 
of  life  (or  cyto-dynamic  principles,  as  they  are  sometimes 
called)  in  such  things.  Another  solution  is  nevertheless 
possible,  for  it  is  conceivable  that  the  life-principle,  or  the 
soul,  might  itself  be  divided  on  the  division  of  the  body.  But 
it  will  at  once  be  objected  that  only  such  things  as  are  quan- 
titatively extended  can  be  thought  to  be  divisible,  and 
quantitative  extension  belongs  to  matter,  not  to  form.  A 
little  consideration  only  is  needed  to  show  us  that  substantial 
form  is,  in  spite  of  this,  divisible  ;  for  it  is  clear,  if  we  take  a 
bucketful  of  water  out  of  a  pond,  we  have  the  substantial 
form  of  the  water  in  the  bucket,  and  another  remaining  in 
the  pond  :  the  matter  being  divided,  the  form  is  divided 
along  with  it.  This  consideration  answers  the  objection,  for 
though  the  substantial  form  is  not  of  itself  [per  se)  either 
extended  or  divisible,  yet  it  is,  or  may  be  both,  by  reason  of 
the  extension  and  divisibility  of  the  compound  of  which  it 
forms  part.  It  is,  as  the  Scholastics  say,  '  divisible  per 
accidens.'  It  is  possible,  then,  that  the  substantial  forms  or 
souls  of  living  things  should  be  divisible.  Is  this  the  case,  or 
are  we  to  adopt  some  other  explanation  of  the  fact  mentioned 
above  that  in  some  cases  living  things  can  be  multiplied 
simply  by  division  ?  Before  speaking  of  the  opinions  on  this 
question,  it  will  be  useful  to  mention  some  instances  of 
multiplication.  In  the  first  place  fission  is  a  common  and 
normal  method  of  reproduction  among  plants,  and  occurs  in 
most  of  them,  a  part  of  the  original  plant  dividing  off  and 
forming  a  new  one.  Gardeners  make  use  of  this  property  by 
taking  cuttings  of  plants,  and  we  all  know  that  a  flower  or 
branch  of  a  plant  does  not  die  immediately  it  is  cut.  The 
same  method  of  reproduction  is  found  among  the  lower  forms 
of  animal  life,  as  in  the  case  of  the  amoeba  and  of  Hydra. 
The  same  is  true  of  the  sea-anemones  and  many  aquatic 
worms.     If  we  turn  to  artificial  division,  we  find  that  life 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  LIFE  187 

can  be  preserved  in  parts  divided  off  from  animals  much 
higher  in  the  scale  than  these.  We  are  all  familiar  with  the 
fact  that  if  an  earth-worm  be  accidentally  cut  in  two  it  will 
regenerate  the  cut  surfaces  and  form  two  worms.  Experi- 
ments have  also  been  carried  out  which  have  resulted  in  the 
preservation  of  life  for  a  time  in  parts  dissected  from  highly 
organised  animals,  such  as  dogs.  Thus  pieces  of  tissue  have 
been  kept  alive  (nourishing  themselves  and  growing)  for 
considerable  periods  :  e.g.  life  was  preserved  for  sixty-one 
days  by  Carrel,  and  for  eleven  months  by  Ebeling.1 

Again,  parts  have  been  transplanted  from  one  animal  to 
another,  e.g.  a  segment  of  the  carotid  artery  of  a  dog  was 
transplanted  on  the  aorta  of  a  cat.  More  spectacular,  though 
less  important  from  a  philosophical  point  of  view,  are  the 
successes  obtained  in  the  preservation  of  the  functioning  of 
an  organ  or  group  of  organs  extracted  from  a  living  animal. 
So,  a  frog's  heart  has  been  kept  beating  for  thirty-three  days 
after  extraction,  and  for  this  it  is  necessary  that  the  muscles 
of  the  heart  should  preserve  their  relations  with  the  nerves. 
Similarly,  nearly  the  whole  of  the  internal  organs  of  a  cat 
were  extracted  and  preserved  alive  for  periods  ranging  up  to 
thirteen  hours  after  the  death  of  the  animal  whose  organs 
they  were.2  Since,  however,  nearly  the  whole  organism  is 
preserved  alive,  while  the  rest  dies,  no  question  as  to  the 
division  of  life  arises,  and  the  rhythmic  pulsation  of  the  heart 
may  be  ascribed  not  to  life  but  to  chemical  action.  It  does 
not  appear,  moreover,  that  in  any  of  the  other  experiments 
we  can  say  with  certainty  that  the  dissected  tissues  or  parts 
were  truly  living,  since  increase  by  means  of  assimilation  of 
nutriment  is  doubtful,  and  reproduction  of  the  cells,  i.e.  the 
production  of  really  new  cells  by  cellular  division,  almost 
certainly  absent.  There  is  purely  dimensional  growth,  not 
organic  growth.  It  does  not  appear,  then,  that  in  the  higher 
animals  it  is  possible  to  preserve  life,  truly  so  called,  with  its 
three  marks  of  nutrition,  growth,  and  reproduction,  in  parts 
cut  off  from  a  living  organism,  though  in  the  plants  and  little 
organised  animals  we  see  that  such  a  process  is  a  normal  and 

1  Journal  of  Experimental  Medicine,  Vol.  XVII,  n.  3,  p.  273. 
*  Cf.  Gemelli,  Religione  e  Scienza,  pp.  134  ff. 


188         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

natural  one.     Is,  then,  the  life-principle,  or  soul,  of  such 
thing  as  these  latter  divisible  ? 

Four  answers  are  given  to  the  question  :  Is  the  soul 
divisible  ? 

1.  The  first  is  that  all  souls,  including  that  of  man,  are 
divisible.  This  is,  in  substance,  the  view  of  materialistic 
biologists,  who,  since  they  consider  living  things  to  be 
merely  physico-chemical  compounds,  maintain  that,  like 
other  compounds  of  this  kind,  such  as  water,  they  can  be 
divided  without  changing  their  character. 

2.  On  the  other  hand,  some  say  that  no  soul  is  divisible. 
Some  recent  writers  (as  Hugon1)  hold  this  view  and  explain 
it  as  follows  :  They  think  that  the  vital  principle  is  actually 
one  and  potentially  multiple.  When  the  body  is  divided  the 
division  must  be  such  that  sufficient  organisation  for  life  is 
preserved,  which  is  an  indication  that  the  soul  as  such  is  not 
divided.  Hence  in  this  view  the  consequence  of  the  division 
is  not  the  division  of  the  soul,  even  per  accidens,  but  the 
induction  of  a  new  soul,  a  soul  which  is  new  in  act,  though  it 
was  present  before  in  potency,  in  the  greatest  propinquity  to 
act.  Hence,  such  a  process  is  more  properly  called  genera- 
tion than  division  of  the  soul,  being  the  origin  of  a  new 
living  thing  from  a  previously  existing  one. 

Mediating  between  these  two  extreme  opinions  there  are 
two  others  : 

3.  Some,  as  Scotus  and  Nys,2  think  that  all  souls,  with  the 
exception  of  the  human  soul,  are  divisible. 

4.  Others,  including  S.  Thomas  and  the  majority  of 
modern  Scholastics,  hold  that  while  the  souls  of  plants  and 
the  less  complex  animal  organisms  are  divisible,  those  of  man 
and  the  more  complex  animals  are  indivisible. 

There  is  probably  little  difference  between  this  opinion 
and  the  second  one  mentioned  above,  except  in  the  mode  of 
expression,  and  which  mode  is  preferred  will  depend  upon 
the  view  taken  of  the  results  of  the  experimental  work  which 
has  been  outlined  ;    for  if  it  be  held  that  life  was  really 

1  Hugon,  Cursus  Philosophies  Thomisticts,  Vol.  Ill,  pp.  64  ff.  Cf.  John 
of  S.  Thomas,  Phil.  Nat.,  Pars  III,  Q.  2,  A.  1  ;  and  Revue  Thomiste,  1923, 
pp.  290  ff. 

8  Nys,  Cosmologie,  Vol.  II,  pp.  30  ff. 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  LIFE  189 

preserved  in  the  excised  tissues,  we  shall  be  led  to  express 
ourselves  as  do  the  exponents  of  the  second  view  ;  but  if  not, 
it  will  seem  more  reasonable  to  say  that,  as  far  as  is  known 
at  present,  the  souls  of  the  more  highly  organized  animals 
are  not  divisible.  In  the  case  of  man,  it  would  be  impossible 
(since,  as  we  shall  see,  his  soul  must  be  held  to  be  simple)  to 
maintain  that  his  soul  was  divisible  ;  nevertheless,  if  it  were 
proved  that  human  tissues  could  be  kept  alive  apart  from 
the  organism,  such  a  fact  could  be  explained  by  the  second 
view,  inasmuch  as  a  vegetative  soul  could  be  generated  in  the 
excised  part  by  the  power  of  the  rational  soul  which  gives 
vegetative  life  to  the  whole  organism,  just  as,  in  fact,  vegeta- 
tive souls  are  generated  in  those  cells  which  naturally  divide 
off  from  the  body,  viz.  the  reproductive  cells.  While  saying 
this,  it  should  be  borne  in  mind  that,  properly  speaking,  it  is 
not  such  souls  which  are  generated,  but  a  new  compound, 
and,  what  is  even  more  essential,  that  the  vital  principle  of 
this  compound  is  not  new  in  the  sense  that  it  in  no  way 
existed  before,  but  only  inasmuch  as  what  was  previously 
potential  now  becomes  actual. *  This  way  of  explaining  the 
matter  meets  also  the  principal  objection  which  is  raised  to 
the  second  view,  viz.  that  we  cannot  say  that  a  new  soul  is 
generated  in  each  of  the  parts  since  this  would  involve  the 
destruction  of  the  original  soul,  which  consequently  could 
not  generate  ;  nor  yet  that  a  new  soul  is  generated  in  one 
only,  since  often  the  parts  are  exactly  alike,  so  that  there  is 
no  reason  for  asserting  that  one  is,  as  it  were,  the  '  mother  ' 
of  the  other.  If,  however,  we  maintain  that  the  potential 
multiplicity  of  the  soul  is  made  actual  in  such  fission,  we  can 
see  that  neither  of  these  statements  need  be  made,  since 
neither  soul  will  be  wholly  new,  but  we  shall  have  two  actual 
souls  where  before  we  had  a  single  actual  one  which  was 
potentially  two.  And  this  is  the  very  way  in  which  S. 
Thomas  speaks  with  regard  to  fissiparous  generation  ;2 
which  is  well  set  out  by  Pere  Sertillanges,  who  says  :  '  The 
degree  of  organisation  of  some  living  things  is  so  restricted 
that  no  particular  organ  is  essential  for  its  life,  or  incapable 

1  Cf.  Cajetan  Comm.  in  I  P.,  Summ.  Theol.,  Q.  76,  A.  8,  n.  10. 
*  De  Potentia,  III,  a.  12,  ad  5. 


190         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

of  being  regenerated  by  the  life  left  in  the  other  organs.  The 
vital  "  idea  "  being  complete  ...  in  each  of  the  divisible 
parts,  to  separate  them  will  produce,  not  death,  but  multi- 
plication. The  soul,  being  simply  the  immanent  "  idea  "  of 
life,  can  therefore  pass  from  unity  to  multiplicity,  because 
from  the  start,  by  reason  of  the  conditions  of  its  support,  it 
was  multiple  potentiality.  The  case  is,  mutatis  mutandis, 
similar  to  that  of  the  homogeneous  continuum,  where 
division  multiplies  the  form  numerically.'1 

This,  then,  seems  the  most  satisfactory  answer  to  the 
question  :  Is  the  soul  divisible  ?  Where  life  can  be  preserved 
after  division,  the  soul  may  be  said  to  be  divisible  per 
accidens  :  by  which  we  mean  that  what  was  before  actually 
one  and  potentially  multiple  becomes,  on  the  division  of  the 
body,  actually  multiple. 

As  far,  then,  as  the  generic  consideration  of  the  soul  is 
concerned,  there  seems  to  be  nothing  in  the  facts  we  have  just 
discussed  to  cause  us  to  assert  that  there  are  many  souls  in 
any  individual  living  thing ;  and  to  that  extent  the  Aris- 
totelean  definition  of  it  as  the  first  act  of  a  physical  organic 
body  is  justified.  We  shall  have  to  return  later  to  the  con- 
sideration of  the  specific  difference  of  living  and  inanimate 
things,  as  well  as  to  that  of  the  positive  reasons  for  asserting 
they  are  essential  unities.  The  discussion  of  the  first  of  these 
problems  will  naturally  occur  as  part  of  that  concerning  the 
lowest  grade  of  life,  the  vegetative,  while  that  of  essential 
unity  will  reappear  in  connection  with  each  of  the  three 
grades  of  life  in  turn. 

1  Sertfflanges,  S.  Thomas  D'Aquin.,  Vol.  II,  p.  88. 


CHAPTER  III 

THE   VITAL   POWERS 

Are  they  Distinct  from  the   Soul  ? — How  are   they  to  be  Distin- 
guished from  One  Another  ? 

So  far,  then,  we  have  seen  that  there  is,  prima  facie,  much 
justification  for  the  supposition  that  living  and  inanimate 
things  differ  in  kind,  and  that  the  generic  consideration  of 
life  does  not  provide  any  ground  for  saying  that  the  life- 
principle  in  a  single  individual  is  multiple.  We  are  thus 
justified  in  asserting  provisionally  that  it  is  one  only,  but 
even  so  it  is  clear  that  vital  activities  are  many,  and  it  is 
natural  to  ask  how  these  two  statements  are  to  be  reconciled, 
and  how  these  manifold  activities  come  about.  This  is  the 
question  concerning  the  powers  of  the  soul  in  general,  and  is 
suggested  by  the  definition  which  asserts  that  the  soul 
informs  an  organic  body ;  for  the  reason  why  the  body  is 
organic  is  that  different  organs  are  required  for  different 
vital  operations. 
Two  questions  can  be  asked  about  these  vital  powers  : 

1.  Do  they  exist,  or  are  they  simply  the  soul  itself  ?  ;  and, 

2.  If  they  do,  how  are  they  to  be  distinguished  irom  one 
another  ? 

Question  I.  Are  the  Powers  of  the  Soul  Really  Distinct 
from  it  ? 
Aristotle,  S.  Thomas,  and  the  Thomists  consistently 
maintain  such  a  distinction  between  the  essence  of  the  soul 
and  its  powers.  There  is,  however,  a  widespread  opposition 
to  this  doctrine,  both  on  its  own  account,  and  also  because, 
owing  to  a  misapprehension,  it  has  been  confused  with  what 
is  spoken  of  as  '  faculty  psychology '  by  modern  psycholo- 
gists, and  which  is,  as  it  seems  rightly,  regarded  by  them  with 
contempt. 

191 


192         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

The  objections  to  the  distinction  in  itself  proceed,  in  the 
main,  from  a  Nominalist  point  of  view,  and  we  find  it  rejected 
by  the  Medieval  Nominalists,  like  Ockham,  as  well  as  by 
modern  Empiricists. 

All  these  recognise  nothing  but  individual  vital  actions  and 
states,  an  attitude  which  clearly  rules  out  any  powers  which 
underlie  these  states  or  any  substantial  principle  of  them. 
All  such  principles  will,  therefore,  be  regarded  as  metaphysical 
phantasms.  Again,  if  it  be  supposed  that  the  faculties  are 
real  agents,  distinct  and  separable  from  the  soul,  the  positing 
of  such  faculties  would  land  us  in  absurdities,  for  it  is  clear 
that  we  can  have  no  willing  without  a  subject  who  wills,  and 
so  on.  This  objection  was  expressed  by  medieval  writers  by 
saying  that  the  soul  is  simple,  and  therefore  cannot  be  split 
up  into  faculties.  Distinction,  however,  does  not  necessarily 
imply  separability.  Perhaps  the  most  common  objection  to 
faculties  nowadays  is  that  they  explain  nothing.  So  Prof. 
Stout  says  i1  'To  say  that  an  individual  mind  possesses  a 
certain  faculty  is  merely  to  say  that  it  is  capable  of  certain 
states  or  processes.  To  assign  the  faculty  as  a  cause  ...  of 
the  states  or  processes  is  evidently  to  explain  in  a  circle  ;  or, 
in  other  words,  it  is  a  mere  failure  to  explain  at  all.'  No 
doubt  in  the  decadence  of  Scholasticism,  and  later,  it  was 
supposed  that  the  question  '  why  do  I  think  ?  '  could  be 
answered  by  '  because  I  have  a  thinking  faculty,'  just  as 
Moliere's  physician,  in  answer  to  the  question  '  why  does 
opium  produce  sleep  ?  '  answers,  '  opium  produces  sleep 
because  it  has  a  soporific  tendency  '  ;  but  this  was  not  the 
intention  either  of  Aristotle  or  S.  Thomas  in  asserting  the 
existence  of  faculties.  They  were  not  interested  in  them  as 
explanations,  but  as  facts.  It  would  be  no  answer  to  the 
question  '  why  does  a  man  see  ?  '  to  say  '  because  he  has  eyes/ 
yet  few  people  would  on  this  account  deny  that  he  had  eyes, 
or  say  that  it  would  not  be  nice  to  mention  the  fact  in  polite 
society,  which  seems  to  be  the  attitude  of  the  critics  of  the 
faculties.  Prof.  Ross2  puts  this  well  with  regard  to  Aristotle. 
He  says  that  Aristotle  does  not  evade  '  the  task  of  genuine 

1  Stout,  Manual  of  Psychology,  Bk.  I,  Ch.  Ill,  p.  114. 

2  Ross,  Aristotle,  p.  133. 


THE  VITAL  POWERS  193 

explanation  of  facts  by  referring  to  a  mystical  faculty  of 
doing  this  or  doing  that.  He  is  simply  taking  account  of 
the  fact  that  the  soul  does  exhibit  a  variety  of  operations 
and  that  behind  each  of  these  intermittent  operations  we 
must  suppose  a  permanent  power  of  so  operating.' 

We  ask,  then,  do  these  powers,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  exist, 
i.e.  are  there  such  powers  really  distinct  from  the  soul  itself  ? 

By  power  the  Scholastics  mean  the  proximate  and 
immediate  source  [principium  quo)  of  action  as  such. 

In  saying  this  they  implicitly  state  with  regard  to  vital 
powers  that  these  are  not  the  fundamental  sources  of  action, 
either  adequate,  since  this  is  the  nature  taken  as  a  whole, 
or  inadequate,  since  this  is  the  soul ;  and,  moreover,  that 
such  powers  are  not  to  be  considered  as  that  which  acts, 
which  is  the  living  thing,  but  only  as  that  by  which  the  living 
thing  acts.  Just  as  it  is  inaccurate  to  say  '  my  legs  dance,' 
but  true  that '  I  dance  with  my  legs,'  so,  strictly  speaking,  it 
is  inaccurate  to  say  '  my  intellect  knows/  and  true  that  '  I 
know  with  my  intellect.' 

That  their  contention  is  true  can  be  seen  if  we  consider 
that  a  living  thing  is  a  substance  and  cannot  therefore  be  a 
power  which  is  essentially  directed  towards  the  production 
of  actions,  which  clearly  are  accidents,  since  they  come  and 
go  in  the  course  of  life  ;  for  it  is  evident  that  two  things 
which  are  essentially  related  to  one  another  in  this  way  must 
be  at  least  of  the  same  generic  kind,  otherwise  they  would 
have  no  community  of  nature,  and  so  would  not  be  essentially 
related.  Consequently  these  powers  must  be  accidental,  and 
so  really  distinct  from  the  constitutive  principle  of  the  living 
thing,  the  soul,  which  is  substantial. 

S.  Thomas  also  advances  a  second  reason  which  applies  in 
a  special  fashion  to  the  soul  as  the  substantial  form  of  the 
living  thing,1  for  substantial  form  not  being  an  efficient  cause 
cannot  be  directed  to  the  production  of  any  effect  beyond 
the  constitution  of  the  compound  of  which  it  is  the  form,  and 
so  not  to  that  of  operations.  As,  however,  we  have  not  yet 
justified  the  statement  that  the  soul  is  the  substantial  form, 
this  reason  can  only  be  noted  in  passing.    The  first  reason  is 

1  Summa  Theologica,  1, 77,1. 


194         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

sufficient  and  we  ought  therefore  to  recognise  the  fact  that 
the  soul  has  powers  which  are  accidents  distinct  from  itself. 
The  recognition  of  this  fact  does  not,  as  we  saw,  afford  any 
explanation  of  vital  actions  ;  but  it  is  useful  in  helping  us  to 
classify  them,  as  is  generally  recognised.1 

Question  II.  How  are  the  Powers  of  the  Soul  to  be  Distin- 
guished from  One  Another  ? 
This  question,  which  is  called  by  the  Scholastics  the 
question  of  the  specification  of  the  faculties,  presents  no 
special  difficulty,  if  it  be  granted  that  the  soul  has  faculties 
distinct,  though  inseparable,  from  itself.  It  must,  however, 
be  clearly  understood  that  in  looking  for  an  essential  dis- 
tinction between  the  faculties,  we  are  considering  them  pre- 
cisely as  faculties,  or  powers  ;  by  whose  means  the  living 
thing  attains  certain  ends,  as,  for  example,  knowledge  of  the 
colour  or  odour  of  an  object.  If,  instead  6i  this,  we  asked 
how  the  faculties  of  man,  for  example,  were  distinguished 
from  those  of  some  other  animal,  the  answer  would  clearly 
be  that  they  were  distinguished  by  being  human  or  not,  i.e.  by 
reason  of  the  natures  whose  powers  they  are.2  Considered, 
then,  precisely  as  powers,  they  are  directed  towards  the  pro- 
duction of  certain  definite  operations,  as  seeing,  etc.,  and 
hence  their  natures  must  be  such  as  will  produce  these 
operations  ;  and  will,  therefore,  be  essentially  different  if 
the  operations  towards  which  they  are  directed  are  essentially 
different.  Consequently,  it  will  be  by  means  of  their  opera- 
tions that  the  powers  of  the  soul  will  be  specified.  But  we 
can  go  further,  for  these  operations  themselves  are  only 
intelligible  and  definable  in  so  far  as  they  are  directed  towards 
certain  objects,  since  what  makes  an  action  to  be  of  a  parti- 
cular kind  is  its  being  directed  towards  a  particular  end. 
The  powers  of  the  soul,  therefore,  will  be  immediately 
specified  by  their  operations,  which  being,  in  their  turn, 
specified  by  their  objects,  the  powers  will  be  mediately 
specified  by  these.     If,  then,  we  wish  to  distinguish  one 

1  Cf.  Stout,  op.  cit.,  p.  115;    and  McDougall,  Outline  of  Psychology, 

P-  13- 

2  Cf.  Cajetan,  Comm.  in  Primam  Partem  Summcs  Theol.,  Q.  77,  A.  3, 
No.  6. 


THE  VITAL  POWERS  195 

power  of  the  soul  from  another,  we  shall  have  to  seek  the 
source  of  this  distinction  in  the  objects  towards  which  the 
soul's  actions  are  directed.  It  is  clear  that  since  we  are 
seeking  a  specific  distinction,  or  distinction  of  nature,  the 
objects  which  will  cause  such  distinction  are  not  those 
which  differ  merely  materially,  but  those  which  differ  speci- 
fically, i.e.  in  nature  or  formally.  Where  we  have  different 
formal  objects,  then,  towards  which  the  vital  activities  are 
directed,  we  shall  also  have  different  vital  powers. 

Distinct  powers,  therefore,  are  necessary  for  different 
classes  of  operations,  as  well  as  distinct  organs,  and  it  looks 
as  if  the  unity  of  the  living  individual  were  seriously  impaired. 
Would  it  not  be  simpler  to  say  that  a  living  individual  is 
really  a  collection  of  differing  living  things  ?  This  suggestion 
is  confirmed  by  the  fact,  which  is  quite  certain,  that  all  living 
things  are  composed  of  cells,  which  are  separated  from  one 
another  by  the  cell-wall,  and  so  are  structurally  discontinu- 
ous. We  see,  then,  that  we  are  constantly  brought  back  to 
this  question  :  Is  the  '  individual '  living  thing  an  essential 
unity,  possessing  one  nature  throughout,  or  should  it  rather 
be  considered  to  be  a  collection  of  distinct  entities  ? 

Though  we  must,  no  doubt,  consider  this  question  in  detail 
later,  in  connection  with  the  three  great  classes  of  living 
things,  it  is  convenient,  and  even  necessary  to  see  whether 
we  can  come  to  any  conclusion  about  it  with  regard  to  living 
things  in  general,  since  we  find  ourselves  hampered  at  every 
turn  through  lack  of  an  answer  to  it. 


CHAPTER  IV 

THE    UNITY    OF    THE    LIVING    INDIVIDUAL 

Opinions — The  Thomist  View — Definitions  of  Life. 

Those  who  hold  what  is  called  the  mechanistic  conception 
of  life,  according  to  which  a  living  thing,  like  a  machine,  is 
composed  of  many  parts  which  have  each  their  own  work  to 
do,  and  do  it  independently  of  the  rest  by  means  of  energy 
given  to  them  from  outside,  answer  our  question  by  saying 
without  hesitation  that  the  living  individual  is  merely  a 
'  colony  '  of  cells  each  living  with  its  own  life.  The  life  of 
the  individual  is  thus  simply  the  sum  total  of  the  lives  of  its 
cells,  and  it  has  no  essential  unity  ;  and,  moreover,  they 
suppose  that  the  cell-life  is  simply  a  chemical  process,  whose 
nature  has  not  yet  been  discovered. 

This  opinion  is  based  partly  on  the  facts  which  we  have 
noticed,  but  still  more  on  a  materialistic  prejudice  and  the 
wish  to  bring  all  the  facts  known  to  us  into  a  form  in  which 
they  can  be  dealt  with  quantitatively  according  to  mathema- 
tical methods. 

Now  the  facts  of  cellular  structure,  and  the  differentiation 
of  the  organs  are  only  a  selection  from  those  which  are  known 
to  us  with  regard  to  living  things,  and  a  wider  view  will  show 
that  not  only  are  we  not  compelled  by  them  to  accept  the 
opinion  that  the  '  individual '  is  really  a  colony  of  cells,  but 
that  they  fit  in  perfectly  with  that  which  is  forced  on  us,  if 
we  consider  the  organism  as  a  whole,  viz.  that  it  is  an  essen- 
tial unity. 

In  order  to  understand  this  we  are  to  observe  that  in  order 

that  there  should  be  essential  unity  it  is  not  necessary  that 

there  should  also  be  material  continuity  in  the  strict  sense, 

i.e.  that  the  extremities  of  the  parts  should  be  the  same.1 

1  Cf.  Cosmology,  p.  67,  and  Ch.  XI. 

196 


UNITY   OF   THE   LIVING   INDIVIDUAL       197 

In  fact  it  is  clear,  quite  apart  from  the  results  of  microscopical 
investigation,  that  the  living  thing  cannot  be  continuous  in 
this  sense,  since,  in  order  that  one  part  should  act  on  another, 
it  is  necessary  that  it  should  be  divided  from  it,  for  otherwise 
it  would  act  on  itself,  so  that  S.  Thomas  says1  that  '  in 
animals  which  move  themselves,  there  is  rather  a  kind  of 
binding  together  of  the  parts  than  perfect  continuation.'  If, 
then,  we  consider  the  living  individual  philosophically,  we 
see  that  all  the  operations  of  its  different  parts  are  related 
one  to  another  and  subordinated  to  one  another  in  such  a 
way  that  each  and  all  are  directed  towards  a  single  end 
which  is  the  preservation  and  the  well-being  of  the  whole 
individual.  Now  this  co-ordination  and  tendency  shows 
that  there  must  be  in  them  some  single  unifying  principle 
which  directs  and  guides  the  various  activities  of  the  living 
thing,  a  principle  which,  in  order  to  unify,  must  be  one,  and 
since  it  directs  the  activities  from  within  must  itself  be 
internal  and  the  principle  of  nature  of  the  individual.  In 
this  the  difference  between  a  living  individual  and  a  machine 
is  evident,  for  the  latter  is  directed  by  some  extrinsic  prin- 
ciple, any  adjustment  either  of  the  whole  mechanism  or  of  its 
parts  having  to  be  made  from  without,  as  is  the  original 
co-ordination  of  the  working  of  the  various  parts  so  as  to 
produce  the  effect  for  which  the  machine  is  intended.  Such 
an  internal  determining  principle  of  nature  is,  as  we  have 
seen,  what  the  Scholastics  call  '  form  ' ;  and  where  the 
nature  is  substantial,  as  in  the  present  case,  '  substantial 
form.'  So  that  we  have  good  grounds  for  asserting  that  each 
living  individual  has  a  single  substantial  form,  and  is  there- 
fore an  essential  unity  ;  so  long  as  we  take  all  its  activities 
into  account,  and  do  not  confine  ourselves  to  some  arbitrary 
selection  made  from  them,  such  as  the  mere  conversion  of 
the  energy  contained  in  foodstuffs  into  that  of  the  body,  or 
to  some  isolated  fact,  such  as  that  the  body  is  composed  of 
cells.  We  shall  see  later  that  the  mechanistic  hypothesis, 
and  with  it  the  contention  that  the  individual  living  thing  is 
really  a  '  colony,'  is  even  incapable  of  accounting  for  these 

1  S.  Thomas  in  VIII  Phys.,  Lect.  7,  No.  8. 


198         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

facts,  since  it  is  impossible  to  make  sense  of  them  unless  the 
whole  organism  be  taken  into  account.  The  differentiations 
of  the  parts,  organs  and  powers  of  a  living  thing  are  so  far 
from  being  incompatible  with  its  essential  unity  that  their 
very  variety,  inasmuch  as  they  are  all  co-ordinated  and  har- 
monise with  one  another,  makes  the  unity  of  nature  in  the 
whole  much  more  apparent  that  it  would  be  otherwise.  Just 
as  if  we  see  a  large  body  of  men  who  all  act  in  harmony  with 
one  another  we  are  much  more  struck  with  their  unity  than 
if  there  were  only  a  few  ;  and  the  more  various  are  the  types 
which  a  body  comprises,  the  more  remarkable  will  be  their 
unity.  Nations  exemplify  this  to  some  extent,  a  union  of 
races,  such  as  is  to  be  seen  in  America  ;  still  more,  the  best 
example  of  it  in  any  body  of  men  being,  no  doubt,  the  Catho- 
lic Church,  which  includes  men  of  all  nations  and  types.  We 
can,  therefore,  assert  without  hesitation,  though  we  shall  see 
as  we  go  on  much  to  confirm  us  in  this  view,  that  every  living 
individual,  i.e.  every  living  thing  which  can  preserve  life  in 
situal  isolation  from  others  of  its  kind,  is  an  essential  unity, 
and  therefore  that  the  Aristotelean  definition  of  the  soul  as 
the  first  act  (or  substantial  form)  of  a  physical  organic  body 
is  justified.  It  follows  also,  since  they  move  themselves, 
that  being  such  unities  their  action  will  be,  strictly  speaking, 
immanent  as  proceeding  from  an  intrinsic  principle  and 
tending  to  an  intrinsic  term,  and  further  that  they  will  be 
specifically  distinct,  i.e.  of  a  different  nature  from  inanimate 
ones.  The  full  discussion  of  this  last  point  must  be  post- 
poned to  another  chapter  when  we  consider  vegetative  life 
more  in  detail.  To  close  this  one  it  will  be  useful  to  set  out 
some  of  the  definitions  of  life  in  general  which  have  been 
suggested. 

In  contrast  with  the  Thomistic  definition  that  a  living 
thing  is  a  substance  whose  natural  property  is  to  be  able  to 
move  itself,  and  to  act  immanently,  the  others  are  very 
vague  and  unsatisfactory.  So  the  Oxford  English  Dictionary 
says  it  is  '  the  property  which  differentiates  a  living  animal 
or  plant,  or  a  living  portion  of  organic  tissue,  from  dead  or 
non-living  matter,'  which  is  to  define  life  by  itself.  Bichat, 
the  physiologist,   has  a  similar  circular  definition ;    for, 


UNITY   OF  THE  LIVING  INDIVIDUAL      199 

according  to  him,  it  is  '  the  complexus  of  functions  which 
resist  death.' 

Somewhat  better  is  Herbert  Spencer's  statement  that  life 
is  :  '  the  continuous  adjustment  of  internal  relations  to 
external  relations.'  This,  however,  merely  describes  certain 
vital  phenomena  without  any  attempt  to  penetrate  to  the 
reason  of  them,  and  is,  therefore,  incomplete  both  physio- 
logically and  philosophically. 

Many  similar  vague  descriptions  of  life  might  be  quoted, 
whose  inadequacy  is  so  evident  as  to  lead  to  the  assertion 
that  life  is  indefinable.1  That  it  is  not  so,  however,  we  have 
already  seen. 

1  Cf.  Shipley,  Life,  ch.  I. 


DIVISION   II.     VEGETATIVE  LIFE 

We  turn  now  to  consider  more  particularly  the  various 
grades  of  life.  It  goes  without  saying  that  we  shall  do  this 
from  the  philosophical  point  of  view,  not  from  that  of  Natural 
Science.  For  the  results  arrived  at  by  the  latter,  the  reader 
must  be  referred  to  books  which  deal  professedly  with 
biology  and  kindred  sciences.1  Our  aim  will  therefore  be  to 
discover,  if  possible,  the  natures  of  the  three  grades  in 
general,  i.e.  to  make  plain  their  generic  character  and  their 
specific  differences. 

1  e.g.  Life,  Sir  A.  E.  Shipley,  C.U.P.  Biology,  Geddes  &  Thompson. 
Home  University  Library.    Life,  Geddes  &  Thompson,  2  vols. 


200 


CHAPTER  V 

THE   NATURE   OF  VEGETATIVE   LIFE 

Opinions — Mechanism,  Vitalism,  Thomism — Reasons  in  Favour  of 
the  Thomist  View. 

Beginning,  then,  with  life  at  its  lowest  level,  in  the  plants, 
since  this  is  the  level  at  which  living  things  exhibit  differences 
from  other  physico-chemical  compounds,  we  are  to  ask 
whether  these  differences  are  differences  of  kind  or  only  of 
degree,  i.e.  whether  we  are  here  dealing  with  a  species  of 
material  things — for  plants  are  clearly  material — which  is 
essentially  different  from  that  which  comprises  what  are 
generally  called  inorganic  ones. 

There  are  three  opinions  on  this  question.  The  first  is  that 
of  the  Materialists,  according  to  whom  plants  are  merely 
more  complex  physico-chemical  compounds  than  are 
inorganic  bodies,  but  are  not  to  be  said  to  differ  from  them 
in  kind.  This  view  is  no  new  one,  being  found  among  the 
Greeks  ;  Democritus,  Leucippus,  Empedocles  and  others  all 
maintaining  that  life  is  merely  some  form  of  matter  in 
motion. 

Theories  of  this  type  were  given  a  new  vogue  in  modern 
times  by  the  speculations  of  Descartes,  who  thought  that  all 
the  actions  of  plants  and  animals  could  be  accounted  for 
purely  mechanically,  and  these  views  combined  with  the 
growing  prestige  and  success  of  experimental  science  led 
eventually  to  the  identification  of  life  with  its  manifestations, 
so  that  it  was  thought  to  be  the  mere  sum  of  all  vital  pheno- 
mena. Such  was  the  view  expressed  by  the  Empiricists,  as 
Hume,  and  in  recent  times  seems  to  be  that  which  was  held 
by  the  eminent  psychologist,  Wilhelm  Wundt.1  We  may 
notice  that  the  mechanistic  view  of  life  is  still  regarded  as 
orthodox  by  biologists  of  the  present  day. 

1  Cf.  his  Einleitung  in  die  philosophic 


202         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

Another  view  has,  however,  been  widely  held  which  is 
diametrically  opposed  to  the  preceding  ;  for  according  to 
many  authors  the  life-principle  or  vital  forces  are  to  be  thought 
of  as  being  essentially  immaterial,  i.e.  as  in  no  way  physico- 
chemical,  but  some  added  unknown  entity.  The  first  to 
make  this  view  explicit  was  Stahl  (i 660-1734),  in  reaction 
against  the  mechanistic  hypothesis  of  Descartes.  He  held 
that  bodily  processes  are  guided  both  consciously  and  uncon- 
sciously by  the  soul,  and  that  it  is  because  they  are  so  guided 
that  living  things  differ  from  inanimate  ones.  This  theory 
with  various  modifications  was  the  predominant  one  from 
the  end  of  the  seventeenth  century  till  the  middle  of  the 
nineteenth.  Prominent  among  its  adherents  were  anatomists 
like  Bichat,  chemists  like  Liebig,  or  medical  men  such  as  the 
members  of  the  Montpellier  school  in  the  eighteenth  century. 
The  vital  principle  was  regarded  as  in  some  way  a  source  of 
bodily  energy,  and  it  was  owing  largely  to  the  breakdown  of 
this  notion  due  to  the  new  discoveries  (by  Mayer  and  Helm- 
holtz)  of  the  sources  of  muscular  energy,  that  the  vitalistic 
hypothesis  came  to  be  discredited  in  the  middle  of  the  nine- 
teenth century  ;  though  it  is  doubtful  whether  an  even  more 
potent  cause  of  this  was  not  the  acceptance  of  mechanical 
explanations  in  science  generally  at  this  time.  The  whole 
intellectual  atmosphere  was  indeed  poisonous  to  vitalism.  It 
is  still  not  dead,  though  at  present  not  popular  among 
scientists.  Indeed  it  seems  to  be  an  hypothesis  with  which 
science  can  have  nothing  to  do,  if  indeed  science  does  not 
deal  with  ultimate  causes  ;  and  as  Prof.  J.  S.  Haldane  points 
out,  it  is  one  which  is  of  no  practical  use  in  biology  and 
physiology.1 

If  we  do  not  adopt  vitalism  it  might  seem  that  we 
should  be  driven  to  a  mechanical  view  of  life.  This,  how- 
ever, does  not  follow,  since  vitalism  as  put  forward  by  the 
biologists  is  necessarily  a  scientific  theory,  not  a  philosophical 
one.  In  order  that  the  vital  principle  may  come  within  the 
scope  of  a  scientific  theory,  it  is  necessary  that  it  should  pro- 
duce some  results  which  can  be  subjected  to  scientific  tests, 
which  will  ideally  be  measuring  tests,  though  in  the  present 

1  J.  S.  Haldane,  The  Sciences  and  Philosophy,  Lect.  4,  esp.  p.  74. 


THE  NATURE   OF  VEGETATIVE  LIFE      203 

state  of  the  biological  sciences  this  ideal  cannot  always  be 
attained.  In  any  case,  in  order  to  be  acceptable  it  must  be 
shown  to  produce  observable  effects  which  cannot  be,  and 
appear  never  likely  to  be,  accounted  for  by  the  observed 
material  elements.  So  it  was  thought  to  be  the  source  of 
physical  energy,  a  notion  which  was  soon  disproved,  and  no 
satisfactory  material  effect  of  the  vital  principle  has  since 
been  substituted  for  this  ;  while  experience  shows  that  the 
progress  of  physical  and  chemical  experiments  constantly 
accounts  for  more  and  more  of  the  hitherto  unexplained 
phenomena  on  a  physico-chemical  basis.  The  abandonment, 
therefore,  of  vitalism  as  a  scientific  theory  only  leads  to  the 
conclusion  that  it  was  not  a  genuinely  scientific  one,  and 
does  not  even  entail  the  adoption  of  mechanism  for  scientific 
purposes,  though  unless  some  alternative  to  it  is  produced, 
no  doubt  scientists  would  work  on  that  basis,  in  the  absence 
of  any  other. 

We,  however,  are  not  concerned  to  discover  a  theory 
which  is  most  suitable  for  the  advancement  of  natural 
science,  but  to  point  out  what  reason  demands,  if  we  wish  to 
avoid  contradictions.  This  brings  us,  then,  to  the  strictly 
philosophical  theory  of  the  nature  of  life  put  forward  by 
S.  Thomas.  With  reference  to  plants,  this  theory  maintains 
that  these  are  not,  in  the  last  resort,  the  mere  sum  of  the 
chemical  elements  of  which  they  are  compounded,  and  the 
forces  of  these  elements  ;  secondly,  that  they  possess  an 
essential  unity  ;  and,  lastly,  that  this  unity  and  the  vital 
operations  of  the  plants  are  due  to  a  '  soul '  which  is  their 
substantial  form. 

The  first  part  of  this  statement  clearly  negatives  a  merely 
materialistic  and  mechanistic  conception  of  plant  life.  It 
cannot  be  proved,  according  to  the  Thomists,  in  isolation 
from  the  second  part ;  since  their  argument  for  it  has  always 
been  based  on  the  fact  of  immanent  action  in  plants,  which, 
as  has  been  pointed  out,  can  only  be  established  when  we 
know  that  the  subject  of  the  action  is  an  essential  unity. 
The  nature  of  this  argument  marks  the  theory  of  a  philo- 
sophical as  opposed  to  a  scientific  one,  since  it  investigates 
the  ultimate  nature  of  the  thing  in  question,  not  those 


-204         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

attributes  which  are  amenable  to  sensible  observation  and 
experiment  only.    The  Thomists  argue,  then,  as  follows  : 

Transeunt  action  differs  in  kind,  or  essentially,  from 
immanent  action,  since  in  the  former  there  need  be  no 
activity  which  is  native  to  the  thing  which  acts,  the  principle 
of  action  will  not  be  within  it,  but  its  action  will  be  caused 
by  extrinsic  influences  acting  upon  it.  So  gunpowder  will  be 
exploded  or  set  in  action  by  a  blow  from  outside,  but  will 
never  blow  up  of  itself  if  it  be  isolated.  Moreover,  it  is  clear 
that  the  term  of  such  action  is  not  within  the  thing  itself, 
but  in  the  launching  of  the  bullet  or  other  external  effect ; 
and  such  is  its  primary  effect,  not  merely  a  secondary  one. 
In  an  immanent  action,  on  the  contrary,  the  initial  source  of 
action  is  in  the  agent  itself  and  is  not  introduced  into  it  from 
without.  True,  it  may  be  stirred  up  or  stimulated  to  act  by 
extrinsic  influences,  but  the  action  though  initiated  by  such 
stimuli  and  using,  in  so  far  as  it  is  expressed  in  physical 
movement,  etc.,  energy  received  from  without,  is  yet  itself 
directed  by,  and  derived  from,  the  agent.  The  term  of  such 
action  also  must  be  primarily  in  the  same  agent  if  the  action 
is  to  be  truly  immanent.  This  being  so,  we  can  see  that  these 
actions  have  nothing  in  common  beyond  the  generic  charac- 
ter of  action,  since  the  thing  which  acts  immanently  makes 
itself  pass  from  potency  to  act,  while  that  which  acts  tran- 
seuntly  does  not.  If  we  now  apply  these  considerations  to 
the  life  of  plants,  it  becomes  plain  that  this  life  is  manifested 
in  actions  which  are,  strictly  speaking,  immanent.  In  the 
first  place  there  can  be  no  doubt  that  the  essential  vegetative 
operations  are  produced  by  the  plant  and  remain  within  the 
organism,  since  they  are  the  operations  of  nutrition,  growth, 
and  generation.  In  nutrition  the  plant  receives  its  nourish- 
ment within  itself  and  assimilates  it  to  itself  ;  in  growth  it  is 
the  plant  which  grows  ;  and  in  generation,  though  it  is  true 
that  the  remote  term  of  the  operation  of  reproduction  is  a 
new  plant  distinct  from  the  old,  yet  the  proximate  term  is 
the  reproductive  cell  which  is  evolved  inside  the  plant  from 
the  substance  of  the  plant  itself,  and  which  remains  a  part 
of  it,  at  least  for  a  time.  In  the  second  place  we  can  see  from 
finality  that  plants  are  substantial  unities,  so  that  the 


THE  NATURE  OF  VEGETATIVE  LIFE      205 

apparent  immanence  of  their  actions  which  we  have  just 
noticed  is  a  real  immanence.  The  test  of  substantial  unity 
is  whether  the  being  under  consideration  is  such  that  all  its 
parts  act  primarily  and  essentially  for  the  good  of  the  whole 
and  only  secondarily  for  their  own  benefit,  for  since  action  is 
to  be  attributed  to  that  which  acts,  where  there  is  an  essen- 
tially unified  action  there  will  also  be  an  essentially  unified 
agent.  This  is  a  consequence  of  the  general  principle  that 
a  thing  acts  primarily  and  essentially  for  its  own  good  and 
only  secondarily  for  some  other  thing,  since  the  source  of 
every  natural  tendency  is  the  inclination  of  the  thing  to  that 
which  is  suitable  to  its  nature,  its  own  good.  Consequently, 
if  a  thing  were  a  collection  of  units  accidentally  joined 
together  it  could  not  act  as  a  whole,  for  the  good  of  the 
whole,  primarily  and  essentially  ;  but  each  part  would  act 
for  its  own  good.  So  if  we  observe  such  action  taking  place, 
we  must  conclude  that  the  thing  in  question  is  an  essen- 
tial unity.  Now  this  is  precisely  what  we  do  observe  in 
the  plants  since  the  actions  of  their  parts  are  primarily 
directed  to  the  preservation,  building  up  and  steady  increase 
of  the  plant  as  a  whole  ;  to  making  good  any  damage  it  may 
suffer,  and  finally  to  reproducing  another  plant  of  the  same 
specific  type. 

We  may  confirm  these  considerations  by  noticing  what 
takes  place  when  life  ceases,  for  during  life  the  vital  opera- 
tions are  directive,  tending  to  a  certain  specified  end,  while 
the  purely  material  operations  in  living  things  are  directed 
by  these  things  themselves.  While  a  body  lives,  all  its 
chemical,  physical,  and  mechanical  powers  are  directed 
towards  the  fulfilment  of  the  purpose  of  the  living  body,  but 
when  life  ceases,  all  these  powers  tend  to  fulfil  their  own 
purpose  independently,  with  the  result  that  the  former 
co-ordination  ceases  and  disintegration  sets  in  in  the 
body. 

The  vital  principle,  then,  in  bodies  is  the  co-ordinating  and 
unifying  principle,  by  which  the  living  thing  is  specifically 
constituted  in  its  being  and  operation  and  distinguished 
from  inanimate  ones.  This  is,  as  we  have  seen,  precisely 
what  the  Scholastics  mean  by  the  term  substantial  form,  so 


206         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

that  it  is  clear  that  the  first  principle  of  life  is  the  substantial 
form  of  the  living  thing. 

It  is  plain  from  this  that  no  living  thing  can  be  a  collection 
or  colony  of  living  beings,  nor  composed  of  a  number  of  sub- 
stances which  remain  actually  and  specifically  distinct  in  it, 
since  its  substantial  form  or  first  principle  of  life  constitutes 
it  as  a  specifically  distinct  being.  If,  then,  it  had  more  than 
one  substantial  form  it  would  be  constituted  a  being  by  one 
of  them,  and  again  so  constituted  by  the  others,  thus  being 
made  over  again  what  it  was  already,  which  is  impossible. 
Hence  the  substantial  form  or  first  principle  of  life  in  any 
one  living  thing  can  be  one  only ;  and  it  itself  must  be  an 
essential  unity  and  not  a  '  colony.' 


CHAPTER  VI 

THE  TRANSMISSION  OF  VEGETATIVE  LIFE 

Reproductive  Processes — Thomist  View  of  Reproduction. 

Before  proceeding  to  deal  with  animal  life,  there  is  one 
function  which  is  common  to  both  plants  and  animals,  about 
which  it  will  be  convenient  to  speak  here  in  a  little  more 
detail,  viz.  that  of  reproduction.  All  material  living  things 
ensure  the  continuance  of  the  life  of  their  species  by  means 
of  generation  or  reproduction.  There  are  two  main  modes  by 
which  this  is  brought  about :  fission,  i.e.  a  division ;  and 
conjugation,  or  joining  together. 

The  first  mode  includes  two  reproductive  processes.  In 
some  cases  a  plant  will  develop  a  little  bulge  on  its  outer 
surface,  which  grows  gradually  larger  and  eventually  breaks 
off  from  the  parent  plant.  These  are  spores,  which  develop 
into  new  plants.  In  other  cases  a  part  of  the  plant  simply 
divides  off  and  forms  a  new  plant  of  the  same  species.  This 
is  called  vegetative  reproduction  and  is  found  very  commonly 
even  among  the  highest  plants.  It  also  occurs  in  the  animal 
world,  but  does  not  reach  very  high  up  in  the  scale.  It  is 
found  among  the  hydroids  ;  and  even  animals  as  high  in  the 
scale  of  development  as  sea-anemones  will  divide  into  two, 
many  worms  also  reproducing  in  this  way.  Such  vegetative 
reproduction  by  mere  fission  is  evidently  a  very  simple  mode 
of  propagating  the  species.  The  name  fission  is  often  confined 
to  the  second  kind  of  reproduction  just  mentioned  where  the 
parts  are  of  equal  size,  as  in  the  amoeba  ;  while  that  of  gem- 
mation is  given  to  the  process  by  which  a  small  bud  breaks 
off  from  the  parent  as  in  the.  yeast-cells.  As  we  ascend  the 
scale  of  life  the  process  of  reproduction  becomes  more  com- 
plicated. First  we  have  fission  stimulated  by  conjugation, 
i.e.  by  the  passing  of  protoplasm  from  one  organism  to  another, 

207 


208         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

as  in  the  case  of  paramcecium.  A  further  stage  is  reached 
when  reproductive  cells  are  formed  in  the  body  of  the  animal. 
These  are  of  two  kinds,  ova  or  eggs,  and  minute  swimming 
cells,  called  antherozoids  in  plants,  and  spermatozoa  in 
animals.  Roughly  speaking,  where  this  is  the  case  we  find 
in  the  plant  or  animal  the  two  sexes — male  and  female — the 
female  producing  the  eggs,  the  male  the  antherozoids  or 
spermatozoa.  These  two,  then,  combine  by  the  penetration 
of  the  spermatozoon  into  the  ovum.  That  this  may  happen 
it  is  clear  that  the  spermatozoon  must  be  separated  from  the 
male  parent,  and  live  a  life  of  its  own  ;  and  the  same  is  true 
to  a  certain  extent  of  the  ovum.  It  is  this  fact  which  is  of 
importance  from  our  point  of  view.  S.  Thomas  and  the 
ancients  thought  that  neither  the  male  nor  the  female  repro- 
ductive elements  were  living,  but  that  both  were  produced 
from  some  superfluity  in  the  nutriment  of  the  plant  or 
animal,  and  not  from  previously  living  parts.  They  thought, 
further,  that  the  female  element  was  merely  passive,  and  the 
sperm  alone  active  ;  the  latter  acting  as  the  instrument  of 
the  generator.  These  ideas  are  clearly  untenable  to-day  : 
for  it  is  now  certain  :  (i)  that  the  ova  and  the  spermatozoa 
are  true  cells  which  are  living  before  they  are  separated  from 
the  organism  ;  (2)  that  the  ova  are  not  merely  passive  in  the 
process  of  generation,  but  active,  though  normally  they 
require  to  be  first  acted  upon  by  the  spermatozoa  before 
they  can  exercise  their  activity ;  (3)  that  the  fecundated 
ovum  (i.e.  after  penetration  by  the  spermatozoon)  begins  at 
once  to  exercise  vegetative  operations,  i.e.  to  nourish  itself 
and  grow ;  (4)  that  the  germinal  cells  can,  even  without 
conjugation,  evolve  themselves  into  a  new  individual,  at 
least  in  some  cases  and  for  a  time.  The  most  common 
instance  of  this  is  parthenogenesis  (virgin-birth),  when  the 
ovum  which  is  not  fecundated  can,  if  placed  in  suitable  con- 
ditions, grow  either  naturally,  as  occurs  in  many  plants  and 
among  the  bees,  where  the  males  are  born  in  this  way,  and  in 
many  other  species ;  or  else  growth  may  be  induced  by 
artificial  means,  as  has  been  done  in  the  case  of  sea-urchins' 
and  frogs'  eggs,  among  others.  The  first  three  facts  require 
that  we  should  admit  from  the  first  moment  of  fecundation  a 


TRANSMISSION  OF  VEGETATIVE  LIFE       209 

principle  of  life  in  the  ovum  as  well  as  in  the  spermatozoa, 
and  all  four  indicate  that  both  male  and  female  elements 
have  vital  principles  of  their  own  from  the  start.  Hence,  we 
have  two  living  beings,  the  ovum  and  the  spermatozoon, 
and  it  is  necessary  to  admit  that  at  the  moment  of  fecundation, 
there  must,  in  order  that  we  may  have  true  generation,  be  a 
corruption  of  the  previous  forms  or  vital  principles,  and  a 
single  new  vital  principle  must  be  drawn  from  the  poten- 
tiality of  matter  :  otherwise  we  should  have  the  union  of  two 
complete  beings,  which  could  not  give  a  single  complete 
being. 

The  most  difficult  case  is  obviously  that  of  man,  since 
here  we  cannot  admit,  as  perhaps  we  might  in  other  animals 
and  plants,  that  the  vital  principle  is  itself  divisible.  The 
process  seems  to  be  as  follows  :  at  the  moment  when  any  part 
of  the  human  individual  is  separated  from  this  individual, 
this  part,  considered  as  properly  a  part  of  the  human  com- 
pound, is  corrupted,  i.e.  loses  its  previous  form  which  was 
the  soul  of  the  man  or  woman.  This  corruption  must  be,  at 
the  same  time,  a  generation.  What  is  it  that  is  generated  ? 
It  may  be  a  non-living  body,  as  when  a  leg  is  amputated,  or  a 
living  one.  In  the  case  of  the  germinal  cells  it  will  be  seen 
from  what  has  been  said  that  it  is  a  living  one.  The  living 
spermatozoon  now  penetrates  the  ovum,  and  gradually  the 
ovum  changes  its  nature  and  becomes  one  with  the  sperma- 
tozoon. This  is  .a  second  corruption  and  generation,  the 
corruption  of  the  previous  forms  of  the  spermatozoon  and 
ovum,  and  the  generation  of  the  new  form  of  the  individual. 
This  form  will  certainly  be  a  vital  principle,  but  these  con- 
siderations afford  no  grounds  for  deciding  whether  it  is 
properly  speaking  a  human  soul,  i.e.  a  rational  one,  or  some 
other  form  of  life.  The  process  is  therefore  much  more 
complicated  than  S.  Thomas  thought,  but  the  essential 
principles  of  his  explanation  by  corruption  and  generation 
are  still  applicable  to  it. 

In  the  case  of  plants  and  animals  their  souls,  forms,  or 
vital  principles  are  universally  recognised  by  Scholastics  to 
be  drawn  out  of  the  potentiality  of  matter,  under  the 
influence  of  the  active  principle  of  life  in  the  parents.    The 


210         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

reason  of  this  statement  is  not  far  to  seek,  for  we  have  seen 
that  all  the  essential  operations  of  plants  are  dependent  on 
matter,  and  so  their  nature  must  also  be  of  the  material 
order  and  dependent  on  matter.  Hence  their  life  will  dis- 
appear on  the  corruption  of  their  bodies,  and  will  also  have 
its  beginning  in  dependence  on  matter.  The  production  of 
these  forms,  therefore,  comes  about  in  just  the  same  way  as 
that  of  the  forms  of  inanimate  compounds  as  outlined  earlier 
in  Cosmology. x  What  is  true  of  the  substantial  forms  of  such 
living  things  will  a  fortiori  be  true  of  those  of  their  generative 
elements  and  cells,  so  that  the  forms  of  the  antherozoids, 
spermatozoa  and  ova  will  all  be  drawn  out  of  the  potentiality 
of  matter,  and  these  in  turn  will  draw  from  matter  the  sub- 
stantial forms  or  life-principles  of  the  new  plants  or  animals. 

What  is  said  here  applies  to  plants  and  animals  in 
general,  but  it  is  evident  that  if — as  we  shall  see  later  is  the 
case — man  has  a  soul  which  is  independent  of  matter  or 
spiritual,  such  a  soul  cannot  be  drawn  out  of  the  potentiality 
of  matter,  so  that  in  this,  as  in  many  other  ways,  he  is  an 
exception  to  those  laws  which  govern  the  animal  world  in 
general.  Nevertheless,  since  it  is  clear  that  the  forms  of  the 
human  spermatozoa  and  ova  are  not  human  souls,  since 
they  are  corrupted  when  fecundation  takes  place,  these  can 
be  brought  out  of  matter  under  the  influence  of  the  life- 
principle  of  the  parents,  so  that  the  first  stages  in  human 
reproduction  will  follow  the  same  lines  as  those  which  govern 
generation  all  through,  in  the  lower  animals  and  in  plants. 

Such  generation,  though  belonging  to  the  material  order, 
is  nevertheless  not  a  mere  resultant  of  physical  and  chemical 
forces,  just  as  the  life  of  plants  and  animals  is  something 
which  is  not  purely  physico-chemical ;  as  Balfour  says  : 
'  though  mechanical  laws  can  account  for  rearrangements, 
they  cannot  account  for  creation  ;  since,  therefore,  conscious- 
ness is  more  than  rearrangement,  its  causes  must  be  more 
than  mechanical.'2 

1  See  pp.  135  fif. 

2  A.  J.  Balfour,  Theism  and  Humanism,  p.  43. 


DIVISION   III.    SENSITIVE   LIFE 

We  can  now  take  it  as  established  that  things  possessed  of 
vegetative  life,  and  therefore  living  things  in  general,  differ 
specifically  or  in  kind  from  inanimate  ones.  The  interest  of 
the  study  of  plant  life  from  the  philosophical  point  of  view 
lay  largely  in  the  fact  that  since  plants  are  the  lowest  forms 
of  living  beings,  it  is  among  them  that  we  must  look  for  the 
line  of  demarcation  between  the  animate  and  inanimate 
realms  ;  and  we  have  seen  that  though  they  possess  much  in 
common  with  inanimate  substances,  yet  they  have  one 
power  which  is  never  found  in  the  latter,  viz.  that  of  imman- 
ent action.  We  are  now  to  go  on  to  consider  whether  we  can 
assert  that  in  the  world  of  living  beings  there  are  similar 
lines  of  demarcation  which  separate  them  into  classes  which 
are  different  in  kind  one  from  another.  If  there  are,  no 
doubt  the  first  will  be  that  which  divides  animals  from 
plants  ;  and  we  ask  therefore  whether  these  two  classes  of 
things  are  in  fact  different  in  kind.  Now  the  distinguishing 
characteristic  of  animals  is  that  they  are  capable  of  knowing 
things  other  than  themselves  by  means  of  their  senses  ;  and 
we  shall  be  justified  in  concluding  that  this  characteristic  is  a 
specific  one  if  we  can  show  (a)  that  they  can,  in  fact,  gain 
such  knowledge,  and  (b)  that  plants  never  can. 


211 


CHAPTER   VII 

COGNIT/.ON 

Nature    of    Cognition — S.    Thomas'    View — The    Materialist    and 
Idealist  Views — The  Thomist  View  Further  Explained. 

What  Do  We  Mean  by  Knowledge  ? 

Before  we  can  discuss  the  question  of  the  distinction  of 
plant  and  animal,  we  must  have  a  clear  idea  of  what  is 
meant  by  the  word  '  knowledge  '  in  general,  and  sensation  or 
sensitive  knowledge  in  particular. 

S.  Thomas'  view  of  the  nature  of  knowledge,  while  based 
on  observation  of  the  facts,  is  worked  out  in  close  connection 
with  his  metaphysical  system,  or  his  general  view  of  the 
nature  of  reality. 

In  all  the  main  questions  which  we  have  so  far  investigated, 
we  have  seen  that  S.  Thomas  finds  his  solution  in  the  applica- 
tion of  the  distinction  between  potency  and  act.  This  is  no 
mere  artifice,  no  '  abracadabra,'  but  something  which  is 
forced  upon  him  by  the  nature  of  the  case  ;  as,  for  example, 
'  time  '  becomes  inexplicable  without  this  distinction,  as  do 
also  the  natures  of  material  things.  As  we  observe  the 
numerous  instances  in  which  this  key  unlocks  the  door,  we 
shall  begin  to  feel  sure  that  it  is  indeed  a  master  key  ;  and 
by  the  end  of  our  enquiry  we  shall  be  quite  certain  of  this. 
The  question  as  to  the  nature  of  knowledge  is  no  exception 
to  our  rule  ;  for  if  we  consider  what  it  is  that  occurs,  at  least 
apparently,  in  knowledge,  we  shall  say,  no  doubt,  that  it  is 
the  union  of  the  knowing  subject  with  some  object  other  than 
itself.  Now  such  union  demands  certain  prerequisite  condi- 
tions, both  on  the  part  of  the  knowing  subject  and  on  that 
of  the  object.  From  the  point  of  view  of  the  object,  the  first 
necessity  is  that  it  should  be  something,  i.e.  something 
definite  and  fixed,  at  least  to  some  extent ;  for  it  is  impossible 

212 


COGNITION  213 

to  have  knowledge  of  a  thing  which  is  in  a  state  of  flux,  or 
altogether  undetermined.  While  we  grasp  it,  it  would  have 
changed,  and  we  could  never  know  it.  We  should  continu- 
ally have  to  say  :  '  I  thought  I  knew  '  ;  we  could  never  say  : 
'  I  know.'  Our  lives  would  be  like  those  of  Lewis  Carroll's 
Mad  Gardener  : 

'  He  thought  he  saw  a  banker's  clerk 
Descending  from  a  bus. 
He  looked  again,  and  found  it  was 
A  hippopotamus.' 

So  we  say  that  gold  is  yellow,  heavy,  opaque,  etc.  If  we 
remove  all  these,  and  every  other  determination  from  it,  we 
can  say  nothing  about  it,  for  we  can  have  no  knowledge  of  it. 
In  other  words,  the  object  can  only  be  known  by  means  of 
its  determinations,  its  constant  attributes,  its  forms.  The 
underlying  substance  or  potency  or  matter  can  only  be  spoken 
of  and  known  in  terms  of  the  act  which  is  proportionate  to  it. 
Thus  only  determinations,  i.e.  acts  or  forms,  are  intelligible. 
From  this  it  follows  that  since  knowledge  is  a  kind  of  union 
between  the  knowing  subject  and  the  object  of  knowledge, 
and  the  object  being  a  determination  or  form,  the  subject 
must  in  some  way  correspond  with  this  form  or  act,  for  it 
must  be  capable  of  receiving  into  itself  the  forms  of  things 
other  than  itself.  Further,  it  must  receive  these  forms  in  a 
peculiar  way.  If  it  simply  becomes  the  things  which  it 
knows,  by  the  reception  of  their  forms,  as  light  becomes 
coloured  when  it  passes  through  a  coloured  glass,  we  should 
not  have  what  we  mean  by  knowledge,  since  this  implies  the 
perceived  union  of  the  subject  with  something  other  than 
itself.  Hence  the  knowing  subject  must  receive  the  form  of 
things  other  than  itself,  not  as  its  own  form,  but  as  they  are 
the  forms  of  these  other  things,  these  known  objects  ;  in 
contradistinction  from  a  nescient  subject,  which  can  only 
have  its  own  form,  or  if  it  receives  those  of  others,  receives 
them,  not  as  they  are  the  forms  of  things  other  than  itself  ; 
since  in  receiving  them  it  makes  them  its  own  form.  So  a 
stone  lying  in  the  sun's  rays  receives  one  of  the  sun's  forms, 
heat,  and  becomes  hot ;  but  the  heat  once  received  is  its 
own,  not  the  sun's.    So  a  cannibal  who  eats  his  enemy  does 


214         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

not  become  his  enemy  ;  his  enemy  becomes  him.  The  know- 
ing subject  which  receives  the  forms  of  other  things  as  such  is 
thereby  made  greater  than  before  :  it  is  enlarged.  For  form 
is  that  which  makes  a  thing  what  it  is  ;  if,  therefore,  the 
knowing  subject  receives  the  forms  of  other  things  which 
remain  the  forms  of  other  things  after  reception,  it  becomes 
these  other  things  in  a  certain  way  ;  and  if  there  are  beings 
who  are  capable  of  knowing  all  things,  these  are  also  capable 
of  becoming  all  things,  and  in  so  far  as  they  do  know,  so  is 
their  very  being  developed  and  widened. 

Apart  from  this  view  of  the  relation  of  subject  and  object 
in  cognition,  which  is  that  of  S.  Thomas,  there  are  two  other 
general  ways  of  conceiving  this  relation,  which,  though  in 
some  respects  simpler  and  more  obvious  than  his,  yet  in  one 
way  or  another  fall  short  of  giving  a  complete  account  of  it. 
On  the  face  of  it,  it  seems  as  if  we  must  either  say  that  the 
cognitive  faculty  is  perfected  by  the  object  which  in  some 
way  changes  it  intrinsically,  so  that  the  faculty  is  merely 
passive  with  regard  to  the  object,  after  the  fashion  of  a 
photographic  film  ;  in  which  case  cognition  will  not  be  a 
vital  or  immanent  action,  which  it  certainly  is  :  or  else  if 
this  last  is  to  be  maintained  it  seems  that  the  object  must  be 
related  to  the  faculty  merely  extrinsically  ;  and  the  faculty 
will  be  active  only  in  the  eliciting  of  its  act,  and  will  not, 
properly  speaking,  know  the  object  at  all,  since  this  will  be 
something  extrinsic  to  its  act.  In  other  words,  we  seem 
to  be  faced  with  the  dilemma  of  saying  either  that  know- 
ledge is  entirely  immanent,  when  the  object  will  not  be 
known,  since  it  is  outside  thought  (or  sensation),  which  is 
the  position  taken  up  by  idealists  :  or  else  that  it  is  not 
immanent,  but  a  transient  action  of  the  object  which 
impresses  itself  on  the  subject,  the  latter  being  quite  passive, 
and  so  not  exercising  any  vital  action,  such  as  an  act  of 
knowing  must  be,  at  all.  This  last  is  the  view  of  the  Materi- 
alists, who  wish  to  reduce  cognition  to  a  physical,  as  opposed 
to  a  psychological,  impression  on  the  organism.  In  either 
view,  therefore,  an  essential  element  in  our  notion  of  know- 
ledge is  declared  to  be  unattainable ;  in  the  first,  that  the 
subject  can  be  united  in  knowledge  with  something  other 


COGNITION  215 

than  itself ;  in  the  second,  the  vital  character  of  the  act  of 
knowledge. 

Now  the  Thomistic  view,  in  asserting  that  those  things 
which  are  capable  of  cognition  differ  from  those  that  are  not, 
in  having  a  capacity  for  receiving  the  form  of  something 
other  than  themselves,  resolves  this  dilemma  ;  for  in  so  far 
as  it  is  the  form  which  is  received,  it  is  clear  that  we  are  not 
dealing  with  a  merely  material  impression,  as  the  Materialists 
suppose,  and  in  so  far  as  this  form  is  not  that  of  the  knowing 
subject,  but  of  the  thing  known,  the  act  of  knowledge  will, 
in  a  certain  way,  extend  outside  the  subject ;  which  will  not 
be  prevented  by  the  prison  walls  of  its  own  self  from  grasping 
objects  outside  it.  That  such  a  process  may  be  possible  it  is 
necessary,  as  S.  Thomas  shows,  that  the  subject  should  be  to 
some  extent  immaterial ;  and  this  will  be  the  very  basis  or 
root  of  cognition. 

After  what  has  been  said  as  to  the  nature  of  knowledge, 
this  further  conclusion  needs  indeed  but  little  elucidation, 
since  to  receive  the  forms  of  other  things  in  so  far  as  they 
are  the  forms  of  these  things  is  clearly  to  receive  them 
immaterially,  and  only  that  which  is  itself  immaterial,  to 
some  extent,  can  do  this.  So  long  as  the  forms  of  the  known 
objects  are  restricted  by  the  matter  of  these  objects,  they 
remain  individual  and  are  incapable  of  being  shared  by  any 
other  thing,  for  matter  limits  form  as  potency  limits  act. 
The  forms,  therefore,  to  be  shared  by  other  things  or  united 
to  them  must  be  dematerialised,  and  in  such  a  state  can 
evidently  only  be  received  by  a  subject  which  is  itself 
immaterial  to  some  extent.  So  a  dog  knowing  a  cat  does  not 
know  it  in  its  material  entity  as  a  whole,  its  flesh  and  bones 
as  we  might  say,  but  knows  certain  characteristics  or  forms 
of  it,  as  its  shape,  smell,  colour,  etc.  It  is  true  that  it  does 
not  know  such  forms  in  general,  but  only  as  they  characterise 
this  particular  object,  and  therefore  the  process  of  demateri- 
alisation  is  incomplete,  but  it  could  not  know  the  object  at 
all  if  it  had  to  receive  it  into  itself  in  its  physical  entity  as  a 
whole,  it  would  merely  absorb  it  into  itself.  Since  it  does  not 
do  this,  and  yet  is  united  to  it,  it  is  clear  that  it  must  be  to 
some  extent  immaterial  like  the  forms  which  it  receives, 


216         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

since  to  receive  others  as  others  is  quite  evidently  not  the 
same  as  receiving  them  as  oneself,  nor  yet  the  same  as  receiv- 
ing them  as  a  compound  with  oneself,  the  resultant  being 
some  third  thing  differing  from  both  recipient  and  the  thing 
received,  e.g.  a  whitewashed  wall.  This  last  kind  of  recep- 
tion is  that  by  which  a  capacity  or  potency  receives  an  act ; 
so  that  if  this  be  ruled  out,  the  only  kind  of.  reception  which 
remains  is  that  by  which  an  act  receives  a  further  act,  by 
which  form  receives  form  ;  and  this  will  be  cognitive  union. 
Thus  we  see  that  the  necessary  basis  of  knowledge  is  that  the 
subject  should  be  actual,  formal,  i.e.  not  merely  potential  or 
material.  If  this  be  true,  and  it  seems  to  be  an  inescapable 
conclusion  from  the  analysis  of  the  act  of  knowing,  it  is 
evident  that  the  materialistic  view  of  this  process  is  peculiarly 
superficial,  for  in  conceiving  of  it  as  material  they  render  it 
impossible.  Probably  the  thorough-going  materialists,  such 
as  the  Behaviourists,  would  admit  this  conclusion  ;  but,  of 
course,  in  doing  so  they  stultify  themselves  since  neither  this 
conclusion  nor  any  other  thing  can  in  this  case  be  known. 
The  Idealist  solution,  though  at  first  sight  much  more  subtle 
and  profound,  is,  on  examination,  seen  to  be  an  incomplete 
analysis  of  cognition  ;  for  while  they  are  right  in  insisting 
that  it  must  be  a  vital  and  immanent  action,  they  cannot  rid 
themselves  of  the  notion  that  such  action  must  be  contained 
in  the  subject  in  a  material  and  quantitative  fashion  ;  and  so 
consider  the  idea,  not  as  something  which  opens  up  on  the 
object,  and  by  whose  means  we  see  it,  but  rather  as  if  it  were 
a  photograph  of,  or  substitute  for,  the  object  enclosed  within 
the  camera  of  our  minds.  Cognition,  then,  cannot  be  mere 
reception  of  some  form,  a  purely  passive  reception,  since  this 
occurs  in  that  imperfect  reception  of  it  which  is  distinct  from 
knowledge,  as  when  the  air  or  water  receives  warmth  from 
the  sun.  It  always  involves  some  efficient  causality  on  the 
part  of  the  subject,  which  will  be  continuous  so  long  as  the 
knowledge  lasts.  Hence  the  undoubted  importance  of 
attention  and  concentration  ;  the  subject  must  not  only  be 
one  which  is  in  itself  capable  of  knowing,  but  in  order  to 
know  actually  must  make  the  effort  to  know.  The  bee  in 
gathering  honey  does  not  flit  aimlessly  from  flower  to  flower, 


COGNITION  217 

as  the  butterfly  does,  but  sucks  each  one  dry.  It  is  impos- 
sible to  pour  knowledge  into  a  man  as  we  pour  water  into 
a  jug.  So,  though  the  cognitive  faculty  is  called  passive, 
inasmuch  as  it  does  not  change  its  object,  but  is  changed 
and  fertilised  by  it,  yet  it  is  indeed  operative  and  active.  So 
Dr.  Ross  points  out  that,  in  Aristotle's  view,  sensation  is 
an  alteration  which  is  '  the  advance  of  something  towards 
itself  and  towards  actuality,'1  and  he  adds  that  '  it  is  only  if 
reception  of  form  means  awareness  of  form  that  it  is  a  true 
description  of  perception.'  Such  activity  is  a  necessary  con- 
dition of  cognition  even  in  its  simplest  forms,  since  apart 
from  it  the  subject  would  remain  involved  in  itself — as 
indeed  the  Idealists  think  it  does — and  there  would  be  no 
distinction  between  it  and  the  world  outside.2  That  such 
'  autonomy  '  of  the  intelligence,  along  with  its  dependence 
on,  and  heteronomy  with  regard  to,  the  object,  is  an  integral 
part  of  the  Thomistic  view  of  this  matter  has  been  ably  and 
lucidly  brought  out  by  M.  Maritain  for,  as  he  says,  the 
intelligence  '  only  knows  the  object  by  becoming  it,  and  this 
of  itself  and  actively,  in  the  final  perfection  of  operative 
activity.'3 

Another  consequence  of  great  interest  follows  from  this 
position,  namely,  that  this  cognitive  union  is  the  closest  of 
all  unions.  For  it  is  closer  than  that  which  joins  form  and 
matter,  since  in  the  latter  case  the  matter  does  not  become 
the  form,  but  is  intimately  united  with  it  to  compose  some 
third  thing,  whereas  in  the  former  case  the  subject  becomes 
the  form  in  a  certain  way,  receiving  it  immaterially.4 

1  Ross,  Aristotle,  p.  136. 

2  Cf.  Selbie,  The  Psychology  of  Religion  (1924),  p.  54. 

3  Cf.  Maritain,  Reflexions  sur  l' intelligence  (1924),  p.  55. 

4  For  a  full  discussion  of  this  point  see  '  Gredt.  De  Unione  omnium 
maxima  inter  subjectum  cognoscens  et  objectum  cognitum  '  in  Xenia 
Thomistica,  Vol.  I,  pp.  303-318. 


CHAPTER  VIII 

THE   PROCESS   OF   KNOWLEDGE 

Necessary  Conditions  for  Union  of  Subject  and  Object — Their 
Assimilation  Involves  Change  in  Both — The  Intentional 
Species — Why  they  are  Necessary — And  Universally  Necessary 
— The  Two  Kinds  of  Species  :  Impressed  and  Expressed — Their 
Nature  and  Mode  of  Production — Their  Precise  Function — 
Are  Expressed  Species  Present  in  Every  Cognitive  Act  ? 

In  order  to  complete  our  notion  of  the  nature  of  knowledge 
it  is  necessary  to  see  how  knowledge,  the  peculiar  kind  of 
union  between  subject  and  object  which  we  have  just  been 
considering,  is  brought  about.  What  is  the  process  employed 
in  knowing ;  or,  to  use  a  metaphor,  which  must  not  be 
understood  too  literally,  what  is  the  mechanism  of 
knowledge  ? 

Broadly  speaking,  two  kinds  of  answer  are  possible,  viz. 
that  the  union  is  effected  either  by  the  action  of  the  cognitive 
faculty  itself,  or  by  that  of  something  other  than  the  cogni- 
tive faculty,  i.e.  by  the  external  object.  The  first  view  is 
that  taken  by  all  the  transcendental  and  objective  Idealists, 
as  Kant,  Fichte,  Schelling,  and  Hegel,  while  the  second  is 
held  by  all  who  maintain  that  our  knowledge  takes  its  rise 
with  things  external  to  us,  or,  as  we  commonly  say,  by 
Realists  ;  among  whom  are  to  be  reckoned  the  Materialists. 
The  view  of  these  last  may  be  at  once  dismissed,  since  it 
neglects  an  essential  element  of  the  problem,  maintaining 
that  the  object  is  present  in  the  cognitive  faculty  in  its 
physical  entity,  whicl.  i^  obviously  untrue,  since  it  is  clear 
that  the  object  is  in  he  knowing  subject  in  a  different  way 
from  that  in  which  it  ex  sts  in  nature.  That  the  view  of  the 
idealists  solves  the  question  of  the  union  of  the  subject  and 
object  is  patent,  since  khe  object  is  thought  to  be  evolved 
from  the  very  fabric  c*  tne  cognitive  faculty,  and  thus,  being 

218 


THE  PROCESS  OF   KNOWLEDGE  219 

the  faculty,  is  evidently  united  to  it.  The  very  simplicity 
of  this  solution,  nevertheless,  indicates  that  it  is  rather  a 
denial  of  the  problem  than  an  answer  to  it.  It  is,  in  fact, 
contrary  to  the  notion  of  cognition  as  being  an  expansion  of 
the  knowing  subject,  by  means  of  which  it  enlarges  its  bound- 
aries to  become  other  than  itself ;  this  view  making  knowledge 
to  consist  in  the  mere  evolution  of  the  knowing  subject  itself. 
Our  conception  of  the  nature  of  this  process  of  knowing  will 
evidently  be  determined  by  the  view  which  we  take  of  the 
nature  of  the  cognitive  union,  and  we  shall  therefore  try  to 
explain  what  this  process  must  be  if  we  accept  that  idea  of 
its  nature  which  is  set  out  above. 

As  we  have  already  remarked,  the  cognitive  faculty,  con- 
sidered simply  in  itself,  is  passive,  and,  consequently,  if  it  is 
to  become  active,  it  must  be  acted  upon  by  the  object.  The 
question  therefore  is  as  to  the  way  in  which  the  object  acts 
on  the  faculty  and  determines  it. 

In  the  first  place  it  is  clear  that  in  order  that  the  object 
may  be  joined  to  the  cognitive  faculty,  these  two  things  must 
be  in  some  way  assimilated  to  one  another,  since  a  thing 
cannot  be  made  one  with  another  which  is  altogether  different 
from  it.  Animals  of  different  species,  such  as  dogs  and  cats,  do 
not  interbreed  ;  and  we  are  here,  in  speaking  of  a  sense  and 
the  object,  dealing  with  two  things  which  differ  much  more 
radically  from  one  another  than  do  animals  such  as  these. 
If,  then,  they  are  to  be  united,  either  one  or  both  of  them 
must  undergo  a  change.  That  there  is  a  change  in  the  sense 
organs  is  clear,  and  is  universally  admitted.  For  example, 
in  the  sense  of  sight,  the  eye  is  affected  by  the  light  waves  ; 
in  hearing,  the  ear  is  affected  by  the  vibrations  of  the  air, 
and  so  on.  Moreover,  the  nervous  system  connected  with 
any  sense-organ  is  affected  by  the  changes  which  occur  in 
that  organ,  and  a  '  stimulus  '  is  thereby  carried  to  the  brain. 
This  being  so,  it  can  hardly  be  doubted  that  a  change  occurs 
also  in  the  sense  itself,  since  this  must  be  affected  by  these 
modifications  of  its  instrument,  the  organ  of  sense.  In  the 
abstract  it  might  seem  that  such  a  change  in  the  sense  was 
sufficient  to  assimilate  it  to  the  object,  and  that  it  is  not 
necessary  to  assert  that  the  latter  is  also  changed,  but  the 


220         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

Scholastics,  and  particularly  the  Thomists,  have  always 
maintained  that  such  a  change  in  the  object  is  essential  in 
order  that  it  may  be  known.  The  object,  according  to  them, 
is  not  known  as  it  is  in  itself  outside  the  mind,  but  by  means 
of  what  they  call  an  '  intentional  species.'  The  object,  of 
course,  as  it  exists  outside  the  mind,  remains  unchanged,  but 
it  produces  a  likeness  or  representation  of  itself,  by  whose 
means  it  exists  in  a  new  way  in  the  animal  or  man  who  knows, 
and  consequently  as  known  it  is  changed.  This  likeness  of  the 
object  is  the  intentional  species  ;x  of  which  the  Scholastics 
recognise  two  kinds,  the  impressed  and  the  expressed 
species  ;  the  first  being  the  form  of  the  object  which  is 
transferred  to  the  cognitive  faculty,  making  it  actively  to 
know  the  object,  while  the  second  is,  as  it  were,  a  sensible  (in 
the  case  of  the  imagination)  or  intellectual  reproduction  of 
the  object  held  up  before  the  mind,  in  such  a  way  that  the 
object  is  known  by  its  means.  It  is  to  be  noticed,  and  we 
shall  later  have  occasion  to  emphasise  this,  that  in  no  case 
is  the  species  something  which,  being  known  first,  leads  to 
knowledge  of  the  subject,  but  always  a  pure  means  by,  or  in 
which  the  object  itself  is  known. 

We  are  here  concerned,  however,  with  intentional  species 
in  general,  without  going  into  this  distinction  between  the 
impressed  and  expressed  species  ;  and  it  is  with  reference  to 
the  species  so  generally  considered  that  S.  Thomas  says  that 
it  is  '  the  likeness  of  the  very  essence  of  the  thing  ;  and  is,  in 
a  certain  way,  the  very  essence  and  nature  of  the  thing  with 
regard  to  its  intentional  (i.e.  mental)  existence  :    not  with 

1  The  reason  why  the  means  whereby  the  object  is  present  in  the 
cognitive  faculty  are  called  intentional  species  is  as  follows.  By  species 
generally  is  understood  the  definite  complete  nature  of  a  class  of  things  ; 
e.g.  the  species  '  man  '  is  the  nature  of  rational  animal  which  is  found  in 
all  men.  Now,  as  we  know,  the  nature  of  a  thing  is  determined  by  its 
form  ;  so  that  intentional  species  are  sometimes  also  called  intentional 
forms.  They  are  called  intentional  to  distinguish  them  from  those  forms 
which  fix  things  in  their  physical  entities  :  substantial  and  accidental 
forms  ;  and  to  indicate  that  they  are  not  something  absolute,  but  essen- 
tially relative,  determining  the  knowing  subject  in  his  '  stretching  out 
towards  '  (intendere)  the  object.  The  fact  that  they  are  called  species  or 
forms,  on  the  other  hand,  makes  it  clear  that  they  are  thought  to  be  the 
determining  elements  of  the  objects  known,  though  inasmuch  as  they  are 
in  the  knowing  subject,  they  are  in  a  different  state  from  that  in  which  they 
are  when  in  the  object  itself  ;  as  will  shortly  be  explained. 


THE   PROCESS   OF   KNOWLEDGE  221 

regard  to  its  natural  existence,  as  it  exists  in  things.1  The 
words  '  in  a  certain  way  '  relate  to  the  different  states  in 
which  this  nature  is  found  within,  and  outside,  the  mind  ;  to 
its  different  modes  of  existence. 

'  Such  a  form,'  as  S.  Thomas  observes,2  '  can  be  considered 
in  two  ways  ;  first,  as  it  is  in  the  knowing  subject ;  and, 
secondly,  with  respect  to  the  relation  which  it  has  to  the 
thing  whose  likeness  it  is.  Considered  in  the  first  way  it 
makes  the  subject  actually  know,  and  considered  in  the 
second,  it  determines  this  knowledge  to  be  knowledge  of 
some  determinate  object.' 

It  is  two-faced  and  two-voiced,  with  one  it  wakes  up  the 
subject,  and  with  the  other  it  introduces  it  to  the  object. 
Considered  in  the  first  way  it  must  be  assimilated  to  the 
nature  of  the  cognitive  faculty,  and  so  be  in  some  way 
immaterial ;  while  considered  in  the  second  way,  it  has  the 
nature  of  the  known  object,  and  is  simply  the  intentional 
reproduction  or  representation  of  it. 

That  the  contention  as  to  the  necessity  of  intentional 
species,  in  order  that  there  may  be  knowledge,  is  justified,  is 
seen  if  we  consider  the  ways  in  which  union  between  subject 
and  object  (which  is  the  very  essence  of  cognition)  could  be 
brought  about.  In  the  first  place  they  might  be  identical, 
and  if  this  is  not  so  the  union  might  be  effected  by  the  object 
being  communicated  to  the  subject  from  without,  either  in 
itself,  i.e.  immediately,  or  by  some  medium.  These  exhaust 
all  the  possible  modes  of  effecting  the  union. 

The  first  supposition  is  in  fact  an  impossible  one,  since  it 
would  imply  that  the  cognitive  faculty  was  identical  with  all 
things  that  it  either  does  or  can  know.  So  Empedocles 
thought  that  the  '  sensitive  soul  is  in  a  certain  way  com- 
pounded of  all  sensible  things  '  ;3  an  opinion  which,  as 
S.  Thomas  points  out,  would  lead  to  two  unacceptable  con- 
sequences, namely,  that  the  senses  could  themselves  be 
sensed,  being  composed  of  actual  sensibles.  and  that  they 
could  sense  without  exterior  sensibles  being  present,  since 
they  themselves  would  be  actual  sensibles.    It  follows,  then, 

1  Quodlibet,  VIII,  A.  4.  *  De  Veritate,  X,  4. 

*  S.  Thomas  in  II  de  Anima,  Lect.  10. 


222         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

that  they  are  only  potentially  able  to  perceive  the  sense 
objects  ;  and  in  order  actually  to  perceive  them  they  must  be 
actuated  by  these  objects,  i.e.  informed  by  them,  not  identified 
with  them.  This  information  cannot,  however,  be  immediate, 
both  because  the  sensible  objects  acts  primarily  by  a  material 
impression  on  the  sense  organ,  and  only  by  means  of 
this  impression  on  the  sense  itself  ;  and  also,  since  the  sense 
object  is  a  finite  entity,  its  form  is  limited  to  that  entity, 
and  so  cannot  be  also  the  form  of  another,  viz.  the  sense. 
If,  then,  the  sense  is  not  united  to  the  sense  object  either  by 
identity  or  immediate  information,  it  must,  if  it  is  to  be 
united  to  it  at  all,  be  so  united  by  mediate  information, 
i.e.  by  the  mediation  of  a  form  received  from  the  sense 
object ;  a  form  which  differs  from  that  which  informs  the 
sensible,  not  in  its  nature,  but  only  in  its  mode  of  existence  ; 
being  to  a  certain  extent  dematerialised,  and  so  made 
capable  of  informing  an  entity  other  than  itself  ;  which  form 
is  what  we  call  the  intentional  species.  Since,  then,  union 
between  subject  and  object  is  brought  about  in  cognition, 
this  result  can  only  be  achieved  by  means  of  intentional 
species  ;    which  must  therefore  exist. 

This  conclusion  holds  good  for  finite  knowledge  of  whatever 
kind,  though  we  have  here  spoken  chiefly  of  sense-knowledge. 
For  it  is  clear  that  in  the  case  of  intellectual  knowledge,  since 
the  object  of  the  intellect,  as  we  shall  see,  is  the  whole  of 
being,  it  would  be  necessary,  in  order  that  the  intellect 
should  be  identified  with  every  being,  that  it  should  actually 
possess  the  forms  of  all  beings  or  be  infinite.  Similarly,  the 
intellect  cannot  be  immediately  informed  by  the  forms  of  its 
objects,  since,  as  we  have  seen,  these  forms,  being  those  of 
finite  things,  are  limited  to  the  things  which  they  inform. 
Hence  intellectual  knowledge  must  come  about  by  means  of 
mediate  forms,  or  intentional  species. 

This  conception  of  the  process  of  knowledge  applies 
universally  to  every  form  of  cognition,  and  we  cannot  make 
any  exception  even  in  those  cases,  such  as  sensations  of 
touch,  where  the  object  is  in  immediate  contact  with  the 
sense  organ.  In  fact  the  species  are  not  required  in  order  to 
transfer  the  object   through   some  intermediate  physical 


THE  PROCESS  OF  KNOWLEDGE  223 

medium,  but  in  order  to  render  it  capable  of  being  known. 
For  this  purpose  a  mere  material  presence  is  not  sufficient, 
otherwise  knowledge  would  be  indistinguishable  from  a 
purely  mechanical  impression,  and  therefore  in  all  cases  this 
material  thing,  the  object,  must  be  in  some  way  raised  to  a 
state  in  which  it  is  to  a  certain  extent  immaterial,  a  function 
which  can  only  be  performed  by  the  intentional  species. 

As  is  implied  in  all  that  has  so  far  been  said,  the  species 
are  required  for  two  purposes  ;  first,  that  the  object  may  be 
made  present  to  the  faculty  ;  and,  secondly,  that  it  may  be 
raised  to  a  condition  consonant  with  that  of  the  faculty 
itself,  since  like  is  known  by  like.  It  is  clear  that  the  inten- 
tional species  are  required  for  the  second  purpose  at  least,  in 
all  cases,  since  the  cognitive  faculty  being  a  vital  one,  is  more 
or  less  immaterial,  while  the  object  of  the  senses  is  wholly 
material. 

So  far  we  have  spoken  of  the  intentional  species  in  globo, 
but  something  must  be  added  on  the  role  of  the  two  kinds  of 
species,  impressed  and  expressed,  which  are  recognised  by 
the  Scholastics.  Without  the  impressed  species  no  know- 
ledge of  finite  things  is  possible,  since  it  is  the  function  of 
these  to  unite  subject  and  object  by  assimilating  the  object 
to  the  subject,  dematerialising  it  to  a  certain  extent.  The 
use  of  the  expressed  species,  on  the  other  hand,  is  altogether 
different,  for  these,  as  we  have  said,  are  likenesses  or  repre- 
sentations of  the  object,  and  are  therefore  only  required 
when  the  object  itself  is  not  present.  From  the  point  of 
view  of  knowledge,  the  object  is  absent  not  only  when  it  is 
absent  from  the  physical  point  of  view,  not  being  presented 
to  the  faculty  at  that  particular  moment,  as  occurs  in  the 
case  of  the  imagination,  and  in  intellectual  cognition  of 
objects  of  which  knowledge  has  been  acquired  in  the  past  ; 
but  also  when  the  object,  though  present  physically,  is  yet 
not  proportionate  to  the  faculty,  as  is  the  case  in  all  intellec- 
tual cognition,  where  the  object  in  itself  is  an  individual  and 
concrete  nature,  while  the  object  as  known  is  a  universal 
and  abstract  one.  The  expressed  species  thus  terminates 
cognition,  not  as  if,  being  first  known  itself,  it  should  lead  to 
knowledge  of  the  object,  but  as  a  term  in  which  the  object  is 


224         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

simultaneously  known.  Cognition  must  evidently,  being  an 
action,  have  such  a  term  ;  so  that  where  it  is  not  already 
given,  as  it  is  in  the  case  of  the  knowledge  of  the  external 
senses,  it  must  be  produced  ;  or,  in  other  words,  the  expressed 
species  must  be  formed.  This  expressed  species  is  called  by 
the  Scholastics  the  image  or  phantasm,  in  the  case  of  the 
imagination  ;  the  mental  word  or  formal  concept,  in  the 
case  of  the  intellect. 

Much  ridicule  has  been  poured  on  the  notion  of  impressed 
species  on  the  supposition  that  these  are  some  sort  of 
effluvia  or  material  particles,  thrown  off  by  the  objects, 
which  fly  across  to  the  sentient  subject.  Though  this  may 
have  been  the  opinion  of  Democritus,  it  certainly  is  not  the 
view  which  the  Scholastics  take  of  these  species,  since  they 
hold  that  the  mode  of  existence  which  the  species  or  forms 
have  in  the  object  and  sentient  subject  is  different,  being 
physical  in  the  one  case  and  pyschical  or  intentional  in  the 
other  ;  not  physical  in  both,  as  would  be  the  case  if  the 
supposition  as  to  their  being  effluvia  were  correct.  Are  we, 
then,  to  suppose  that  the  species  are  entirely  spiritual  and 
not  material  at  all  ?  This  cannot  be  held  either,  since  in  this 
case  no  cause  could  be  assigned  of  their  production,  both  the 
object  and  the  percipient  being  material  things,  and  so 
incapable  of  producing  something  purely  spiritual.  If,  then, 
they  are  neither  wholly  material  nor  wholly  spiritual,  they 
must  be  something  intermediate,  and  are  to  be  called  material 
in  so  far  as  they  belong  to  the  material  order,  but  not  material 
in  the  sense  in  which  physical  and  chemical  forces  are.  Their 
nature,  in  fact,  must  exactly  correspond  with  that  of  the 
sentient  organism  which  receives  them,  and  this  is  itself 
something  belonging  to  the  material  world  ;  though  its 
forces,  since  it  is  living,  are  not  purely  chemical  and  physical 
ones. 

In  order  to  obtain  a  thorough  grasp  of  the  Thomistic 
theory  of  intentional  species,  it  is  important  to  understand 
the  way  in  which  it  envisages  their  production.  In  the  first 
place,  it  should  be  noted  that  what  an  agent  communicates 
is  not  its  matter  but  its  form,  as  S.  Thomas  explains,1  point- 

1  II  de  Anima,  Lect.  24. 


THE  PROCESS  OF  KNOWLEDGE  225 

ing  out  that  though  every  thing  which  is  acted  on  receives 
from  the  agent  a  form  which  is  to  some  extent  without 
matter,  yet  there  is  a  difference  between  the  way  in  which  a 
merely  physical  subject  receives  forms,  and  that  in  which  a 
knowing  or  percipient  subject  does  so.  The  physical  thing 
receives  the  form  with  the  same  material  disposition  to  the 
form  as  is  present  in  the  agent,  so  that  it  cannot  be  said  to 
receive  the  form  wholly  without  matter,  even  though  it  does 
not  receive  the  very  same  matter  as  is  in  the  agent.  He 
exemplifies  this  by  the  case  of  air  warmed  by  the  fire,  which 
in  the  process  receives  the  same  material  disposition  to  the 
form  of  heat  which  was  present  in  the  fire,  even  though  it 
does  not  receive  the  wood  or  coal.  It  is  materially  changed, 
and  not  formally  only.  This  holds  good  of  the  action  of  all 
merely  physical  subjects  of  action,  but  in  the  case  of  per- 
cipient or  cognitive  subjects  it  is  not  true,  since  these  receive 
the  form  from  the  agent  or  object,  without  receiving  the  same 
material  dispositions  to  that  form  as  were  present  in  the 
object,  and,  in  fact,  they  remain  unchanged  with  regard  to 
their  physical  being  after  the  reception  of  the  form.  Conse- 
quently the  similarity  between  the  subject  and  object  is  one, 
not  of  nature,  but  of  representation.  The  species,  there- 
fore, are  produced  by  the  objects,  but  their  mode  of  being  in 
the  subject  depends  on  the  nature  of  that  subject,  which, 
being  a  cognitive  one,  receives  them  without  their  material 
dispositions.  They  are,  as  it  were,  filtered  by  the  subject 
which  receives  them  ;  so  that  their  partially  immaterial 
character  is  accounted  for.  We  can  understand  the  reception 
by  the  subject  of  these  intentional  forms  more  clearly  if  we 
consider  that  every  form  makes  its  subject  to  be  of  a  parti- 
cular kind,  as  the  form  of  heat  (an  accidental  one)  makes  the 
subject  hot,  and  the  form  of  life  (a  substantial  one)  makes 
the  subject  living.  Now  these  intentional  forms  make  the 
subject  actually  knowing ;  leaving  it,  however,  physically 
unchanged  ;  and  simply  determining  it  to  pass  from  the 
capacity  or  potentiality  for  knowledge  to  the  act  of  cognition. 
Hence  the  intentional  form  does  not  make  the  subject 
physically  of  a  particular  kind,  but  simply  makes  it  an 
actually  knowing  subject ;  so  that  it  gives  it  no  other  fresh 


226         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

being  than  that  by  which  it  is  constituted  as  formally  a 
knowing  subject.  The  species,  then,  though  resembling 
other  forms  in  making  the  subject  to  be  of  a  particular  kind, 
yet  differ  markedly  from  these  others  in  not  being  the 
source  of  the  operations  which  follow  on  them  ;  since  the 
operation  which  follows  on  intentional  species,  viz.  the  act  of 
cognition,  is  generated  by  the  cognitive  faculty.  This  is  clear, 
since  the  impressed  species  simply  determines  the  faculty  to 
know,  while  the  expressed  species  follows  on  cognition,  and 
is  that  in  which  the  subject  formally  has  knowledge. 

So  Cajetan1  explains  the  difference  between  cognitive  and 
nescient  things  by  pointing  out  that  the  latter  receive  their 
forms  by  the  operation  of  some  extrinsic  agent,  which  acts 
efficiently  on  them  ;  while  the  former  do  not  receive  their 
forms  from  the  external  object,  which  is  known,  but  are 
made  formally  or  actually  knowing  by  means  of  the  exercise 
of  their  own  operation,  when  they  are  actuated  or  specified 
by  a  certain  object,  i.e.  when  their  attention  is  caught  by  it ; 
so  that  the  efficient  principle  which  makes  them  actually 
knowing  is  the  cognitive  faculty  itself,  and  not  something 
external. 

We  can  thus  understand  the  statement  which  S.  Thomas 
often  makes  :  '  The  sense  in  act  is  the  sensible  in  act,  and 
the  intellect  in  act  is  the  thing  understood  in  act '  ;  for  the 
form  of  the  known  object,  the  intentional  species,  does  not 
combine  with  the  faculty  to  compose  some  third  thing,  as  is 
the  case  in  nescient  subjects,  when  matter  and  form  combine, 
but  simply  actuates,  or  calls  out,  the  operation  of  sensing  or 
understanding.  In  this  way  the  form  of  the  object  becomes 
the  form  of  faculty,  which  so  informed  or  actuated,  therefore 
becomes  the  object  in  the  psychic  order,  though,  of  course, 
remaining  unchanged  as  regards  its  own  nature  in  the 
physical  order.  Further,  it  is  clear  how  the  species  con- 
tributes to  cognition,  for  if  it  be  considered  in  relation  to  the 
object  by  which  it  is  produced,  it  must  be  said  to  be  the 
instrument  which  the  object  uses  to  determine  the  faculty, 
so  that  both  it  and  the  object  contribute  to  the  production 
of  knowledge.    Since,  however,  it  is  the  active  force  by  which 

1  Comtn.  in  S.  Theol.,  1.14,1. 


THE  PROCESS  OF  KNOWLEDGE  227 

the  object  produces  its  effect,  it  is  correct  to  say  that  the 
object  is  an  immediate  contributory  principle  of  knowledge, 
for  the  active  force  of  a  substance  is  to  be  attributed  to  the 
substance  itself,  as  Cajetan  says  :  '  Accidentalis  vis  non  sua, 
sed  substantia  est  virtus.'  If,  on  the  other  hand,  the  species 
be  considered  in  relation  to  the  cognitive  faculty,  we  must, 
as  we  have  seen,  say  that  it  is  the  faculty  which  is  the  active 
cause  of  cognition,  though  it  is  only  so  active  under  the 
actuation  and  determination  of  the  species,  which  can  there- 
fore be  called,  to  this  extent,  an  active  principle  ;  inasmuch 
as  it,  in  union  with  the  knowing  subject,  constitutes  a  single 
principle  of  cognition.1 

If  it  be  true,  as  is  said  above,  that  the  function  of  the  ex- 
pressed species  is  to  be  the  term  of  the  act  of  cognition  when 
the  object  is  either  not  present  or  not  proportionate  to  the 
cognitive  faculty,  it  is  easy  to  see  what  answer  must  be  given 
to  the  question  whether  such  species  are  present  in  every 
cognitive  act ;  a  question  which  has  been  hotly  disputed 
among  Scholastics.  The  question  may  be  put  in  other  forms 
besides  the  one  just  mentioned,  for  if  it  be  maintained,  as  is 
done  by  some  recent  Scholastics,  that  the  expressed  species 
is  only  logically  distinct  from  the  act  of  knowledge,  it  is  clear 
that  it  will  be  present  in  all  such  acts,  so  that  to  ask  whether 
this  distinction  is  real,  or  logical  only,  is  a  second  form  of  the 
question.  Again,  an  action  which  is  always  directed  towards 
the  production  of  a  term  is  called  a  predicamental  action, 
while  one  which  is  not  so  directed,  and  produces  nothing  but 
the  reality  of  the  action  itself,  is  called  a  metaphysical  one. 
So  the  question  can  also  be  put  in  the  form  of  asking  whether 
the  cognitive  act  is  a  predicamental  or  metaphysical  one, 
since  in  the  former  case  it  will  always  be  directed  towards 
the  production  of  the  expressed  species.  The  Thomists,  as 
against  Suarez,  unanimously  teach  that  no  expressed  species 
is  produced  in  the  acts  of  external  Sense  knowledge  ;  and 
this  for  several  reasons.  First,  because  such  species  would 
be  useless,  since  the  object  is  itself  sufficient  to  terminate  the 
act ;  and,  secondly,  it  would  be  positively  harmful,  since  it 

1  Cf.  S.  Thomas,  De  Veritate,  Q.  8,  A.  5  and  6  in  corp.  and  A.  7  resp., 
ad  2um  (of  the  last  series). 


228         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

would  prevent  the  sense  from  grasping  its  object  immediately ^ 
so  that  we  should  have  experience,  not  of  the  object,  but  of 
the  species.  Thirdly,  the  view  that  the  expressed  species  is 
really  identical  with  the  cognitive  act  is  untenable,  since  the 
species  is  that  in  which  the  object  is  known  ;  whereas  the 
cognitive  act  cannot  be  said  to  be  that  in  which  the  object  is 
known  ;  but  only  that  by  which  we  know  it,  without  abandon- 
ing the  Thomistic  theory  completely,  and  adopting  a  purely 
conceptualist  one  ;  since  the  act  of  knowing  must  be  some- 
thing entirely  our  own  or  subjective.  Hence  we  are  not 
obliged  to  posit  an  expressed  species  in  all  cognition  on  the 
ground  that  it  is  identical  with  the  cognitive  act.  Lastly,  it 
seems  clear  that  cognition  is  not  designed  for  the  production  of 
a  term,  since,  even  when  a  term  is  produced,  as  in  intellectual 
knowledge,  the  cognition  continues  after  its  production,  and 
is,  in  fact,  perfected  and  completed  by  the  contemplation  of 
the  term  produced,  whereas  in  a  predicamental  action,  the 
action  ceases  once  the  term  has  been  produced.  The  fact, 
then,  that  the  perfection  of  cognition  comes  about  after  the 
term  has  been  produced,  shows  that  this  production  is 
achieved  for  the  sake  of  cognition  and  not  vice  versa,  as 
would  be  the  case  if  cognition  were  a  predicamental  action, 
instead  of  being,  as  it  is,  a  metaphysical  one  ;  and  so,  a  dis- 
position or  quality  of  the  subject. 

This  doctrine  brings  out  the  true  immanence  of  knowledge, 
inasmuch  as  the  act  of  knowledge  is  something  perfect,  and 
complete  in  itself,  and  not  designed  to  produce  something 
other  than  itself,  while  at  the  same  time  it  gives  no  support 
to  Idealist  theories  of  knowledge  according  to  which  we  only 
know  our  own  mental  acts  ;  since  it  maintains  that  the 
object  is  known,  either  in  itself,  or  in  a  representation  which 
is  really  distinct  from  the  act  of  knowing.  Cognition,  conse- 
quently, is  rightly  denned  as  metaphysical  action,  by  means 
of  which  possession  is  taken  of  a  form  immaterially,  i.e.  with- 
out the  potentiality  of  matter.  So  cognition,  as  such,  has 
nothing  to  say  to  matter,  to  potentiality,  to  imperfection  ; 
and  consequently  is  what  the  Scholastics  call  '  a  simply 
simple  perfection,'  i.e.  one  which  in  itself  involves  no 
imperfection. 


CHAPTER  IX 

SENSE   KNOWLEDGE 

The  Senses  are  Organic — Their  Distinction  and  Number — Where 
Sensation  Takes  Place — The  Objects  of  the  Senses — Immediate 
and  Mediate  Sense  Objects — Can  we  be  said  to  Sense  the 
Externality  of  an  Object  ? — The  Inversion  of  the  Retinal 
Image — Internal  Sensibility — The  Sensitive  Appetite. 

After  this  consideration  of  the  nature  and  process  of 
knowledge  in  general,  we  can  now  pass  to  that  of  the  know- 
ledge of  the  senses,  of  sensation.  In  doing  so  we  shall  first 
investigate  the  nature  of  the  senses  in  general,  and  then  the 
different  kinds  of  sense. 

We  ask,  then,  in  the  first  place,  whether  the  senses  are 
organic  or  inorganic  faculties,  i.e.  whether  they  are  depen- 
dent on  the  organism  or  not. 

That  sensation  is  a  vital  action,  by  which  the  sentient  sub- 
ject knows  corporeal  objects,  which  act  on  the  sense  organs,  is 
hardly  open  to  dispute  ;  and  it  follows  that  three  things  are 
required  for  sensation  :  (i)  an  object,  (2)  an  impression  made 
by  that  object,  and  (3)  that  the  sense  which  is  thus  affected 
should  really  know  the  object,  i.e.  sensation  is  a  kind  of 
cognition. 

By  a  sensitive  faculty  we  mean  a  proximate  and  immediate 
principle  of  cognition  by  means  of  which  the  sentient  subject 
is  united  to  material  things. 

In  asking  whether  such  faculties  are  organic  or  not  we  mean 
to  enquire  whether  they  are  dependent,  for  their  existence 
and  action,  on  the  whole  organic  compound,  on  the  material 
organism  itself  ;  and  we  presuppose  that  sensation  cannot  be 
explained  merely  mechanically,  since  it  is  a  kind  of  cognition, 
which,  as  we  have  seen,  in  our  discussion  of  cognition  in 
general,  cannot  be  a  merely  mechanical  process.  Are  we, 
then,  to  adopt  the  opinion  which  is  at  the  opposite  extreme 

229 


230         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

to  this  materialistic  one  and  say  that  the  senses  depend 
intrinsically  only  on  the  vital  principle  or  soul ;  a  view 
maintained,  at  least  with  regard  to  human  sensations,  by  the 
Cartesians. 

This  question  is  of  considerable  importance,  since  it  deals 
with  the  relations  of  soul  and  body,  and  if  sensation  be  allowed 
to  be  an  act  of  the  soul  alone,  then,  first,  we  shall  have  to 
prove  in  some  other  way,  than  by  its  intrinsic  dependence  on 
the  body,  that  the  soul  is  its  substantial  form  ;  or  else  con- 
cede that  an  animal  is  not  an  essential  unity,  but  a  duality, 
composed  of  two  complete  and  heterogeneous  substances. 
The  opinion  of  the  Cartesians  was,  in  fact,  due  to  their  taking 
this  latter  view  of  the  nature  of  man.  Moreover,  whatever 
we  say  about  this  question  of  essential  union,  it  would  be 
difficult  to  deny  that  the  sensitive  soul  is,  of  its  own  nature, 
and  consequently  in  the  lower  animals  as  well  as  in  man, 
spiritual  and  immortal.  If,  however,  we  establish  that  the 
senses  are  organic  it  will  naturally  follow  that  the  animal  is 
an  essential  unity,  since  it  operates  as  a  whole,  and  conse- 
quently that  its  soul  is  its  substantial  form,  and  also  that  it 
is  not  spiritual.  Further,  we  shall  have  prepared  the  way 
for  showing  that  the  intellectual  soul  in  man  is  the  form  of 
the  body,  even  though  it  may  be  spiritual ;  since  in  man  the 
principle  of  sensation  and  intelligence  is  the  same. 

Actually  the  proposition  that  the  senses  are  organic  is  one 
which  is  not  likely  to  meet  with  much  opposition  at  the 
present  day,  when  the  tendency  is  to  take  a  materialistic 
rather  than  an  immaterialist  view  of  vital  processes.;  and 
S.  Thomas  gives  us  a  simple,  but  convincing,  reason  for 
granting  that  i+  is  true.  For,  as  he  points  out,1  if  the 
operations  of  the  senses  are  intrinsically  dependent  on  the 
organism  the  senses  themselves  must  also  be  intrinsically 
dependent.  Now  it  is  clear  that  sensation  does  depend 
intrinsically  on  the  organism,  since  experience  shows  :  first, 
that  the  objects  of  the  senses  are  always  singular  and  con- 
crete things,  which  could  only  affect  the  sensitive  faculty  by 
a  physical  impression  on  something  material,  viz.  the  organ 
of  sense  ;    secondly,  that  the  sense  itself  is  affected  and 

1  Summa  Theologica,  1.77,5. 


SENSE   KNOWLEDGE  231 

weakened  by  the  physical  forces  of  the  object,  as  sight  is  by 
too  much  light,  or  light  of  an  unsuitable  kind,  touch  by  too 
much  pressure,  and  so  on,  and  that  it  is  sometimes  destroyed 
by  the  corruption  of  the  organ  of  sense  ;  and,  thirdly,  that 
the  sense  perceives  all  things  as  extended,  i.e.  material.  For 
all  these  reasons,  then,  we  are  justified  in  asserting  that  the 
sense  operations  are  intrinsically  dependent  on  the  matter 
of  the  organism  ;  and  consequently  that  the  senses  them- 
selves are  organic. 

We  can  now  turn  to  a  more  detailed  consideration  of  the 
particular  senses.  It  is  at  once  obvious  that  the  sensations 
of  which  we  are  aware  are  of  very  different  kinds.  So,  e.g.  the 
sensation  of  seeing  an  object  is  quite  different  from  that  of 
hearing  a  sound  ;  and  consequently  in  trying  to  classify 
sensations  we  shall  soon  pick  out  what  are  commonly  called 
the  five  senses  of  sight,  hearing,  smell,  taste,  and  touch. 
Common  observation  had  always  distinguished  these  five 
senses,  but  from  a  philosophical  point  of  view  the  division  is 
arrived  at  by  considering  the  objects  from  which  the  sensa- 
tions are  derived,  viz.  colour,  sound,  odour,  savour,  and 
tangible  quality.  It  is  clear  that  to  say  that  the  object  of 
touch  is  what  can  be  sensed  by  touch  is  to  say  nothing  ;  and, 
in  fact,  this  sense  has  a  very  indefinite  outline,  and  is  really 
a  genus  of  sensation  covering  both  sensations  of  pressure,  or 
resistance,  as  well  as  those  of  temperature — of  heat  and  cold. 
What  are  called  nowadays  '  organic  sensations,'  viz.  those 
connected  with  internal  feeling  of  the  organism,  as  sensations 
in  the  stomach,  bowels,  etc.,  as  well  as  muscular  sensations, 
and  so  on,  all  come  under  this  head.  Sensations  of  touch, 
moreover,  are  generally  present  along  with  the  sensations  of 
the  other  four  senses,  particularly  in  tasting  and  smelling, 
though  they  are  also  present  to  some  extent,  generally  with- 
out our  being  aware  of  it,  in  seeing  and  hearing. 

Nevertheless,  since  in  the  last-named  sensations  we  do  not 
know,  by  pure  sensation,  that  the  objects  of  sight  and  hear- 
ing are  acting  causally  on  our  organs,  but  regard  them  as 
being  things  not  in  contact  with  our  bodies,  these  two  senses 
are  often  named  by  the  Scholastics  the  superior  senses,  while 
those  senses  in  whose  action  we  are  aware  of  causal  action  of 


232         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

the  objects  on  the  organism,  in  the  sensation  itself,  are  called 
the  inferior  ones,  viz.  smell,  taste,  and  touch. 

Some  remarks  may  be  made  about  particular  aspects  of 
the  sensations  of  these  inferior  senses.  With  regard  to  the 
sense  of  touch,  touch-sensations  include,  as  we  said,  those  of 
heat  and  cold.  There  are  spots  on  the  skin,  known  as  heat 
and  cold  spots,  and  also  areas  covering  a  system  of  nerve- 
endings,  at  which  sensations  of  heat  and  cold  are  aroused  on 
contact  with  points  or  surfaces.  Pain  sensations  are  also 
included  under  the  sensations  of  touch  ;  but,  of  course,  such 
sensations  are  not  to  be  confused  with  feelings  of  pain,  which 
belong  to  the  affections  or  emotions.  With  regard  to  the 
sense  of  taste,  there  seem  to  be  only  four  or  five  savours 
properly  so-called  :  sweet,  sour,  bitter,  salt,  and  alkaline. 
The  variety  of  savours  which  we  usually  suppose  ourselves 
to  recognise  are  a  combination  of  taste  and  smell.  Odours, 
lastly,  are  almost  impossible  to  classify,  owing  to  their 
variety  and  composite  character. 

Each  of  the  sense  organs  is  connected  with  areas  in  the 
brain  by  means  of  the  nervous  system,  of  which  the  auditory, 
visual,  and  olfactory  areas  have  been  most  definitely  located. 

In  view  of  this  fact  many  modern  psychologists  consider 
that  sensation  takes  place  in  these  sensory  areas,  i.e.  that  we 
actually  sense,  not  in  the  sense  organs,  but  in  the  brain. 
This  opinion  seems  to  have  been  too  hastily  arrived  at ;  for 
it  is  based  on  the  fact,  or  supposed  fact,  that  if  the  sensory 
area  in  the  brain  is  destroyed,  the  corresponding  sensation 
does  not  take  place.  This  fact  would  only  show  that  the 
brain  plays  an  essential  part  in  sensation  ;  and  does  not 
warrant  the  conclusion  that  it  is  the  brain  alone  which 
senses.  On  the  other  hand,  we  have  positive  reasons  for 
adhering  to  the  opinion  that  sensation  takes  place  in  the 
sense-organs,  and  is  thence  carried  by  way  of  the  nervous 
system  to  the  brain,  so  that  we,  as  subjects,  become  fully 
conscious  of  it,  only  on  the  completion  of  this  process.  This 
view  is  in  accord  with  the  strong  testimony  of  experience,  in 
so  far  as  we  always  localise  our  sensations  in  a  particular 
part  of  the  body  :  e.g.  in  the  leg  or  arm,  and  the  fact  that 
a  man  may  '  feel '  sensations  in  an  amputated  limb  only 


SENSE   KNOWLEDGE  233 

shows  how  strong  is  habitual  imagination,  which,  when  the 
nerved,  before  connected  with  that  limb,  are  affected,  still 
persists  in  localising  the  sensation  in  the  absent  limb  ;  not 
that  when  the  limb  is  present  the  man  really  had  no  sensation 
in  it.  The  testimony  of  common  experience,  then,  ought  not 
to  be  reckoned  erroneous,  unless  there  be  some  certain  reason 
which  renders  it  untenable.  Such  a  reason  was  thought  to 
be  the  fact  that  impressions  of  light  and  sound  could  be 
engendered  by  direct  excitation  of  the  visual  and  auditory 
centres  ;  but  it  should  be  noticed  that  it  does  not  seem  poss- 
ible to  do  this  in  subjects  which  have  never  possessed  the 
sense  in  question  ;  and,  moreover,  the  impressions  so  pro- 
duced are  not  of  any  determinate  object,  but  indefinite 
ones  of  illumination  or  noise,  etc.,  in  which,  again,  imagina- 
tion would  have  a  part  to  play.  The  opinion  we  are  oppos- 
ing seems  to  rest  on  an  inveterate  prejudice  that  the 
organism  is  really  a  mere  mechanism,  like  a  photographic 
camera,  so  that  the  organs  and  nerves  could  only  be  mere 
media  to  transmit  a  physico-chemical  impulse  to  a  purely 
material  receptacle,  and  so  could  not  be  said  to  receive  the 
impressions  themselves.  If,  however,  we  reject  this  view  as 
being  a  merely  a  priori  one,  as  it  is,  and  founding  ourselves  on 
experience,  maintain  that  the  organism  acts  as  a  vital  whole, 
there  seems  to  be  no  reason  for  abandoning  the  doctrine  that 
sensation  takes  place,  i.e.  the  object  is  sensed  primarily,  in 
the  organs  on  the  body's  surface,  and  is  completed,  and  made 
fully  conscious,  when  their  impressions  affect  the  sensory 
areas  in  the  brain  ;  and  so  the  general  sensitivity,  and  the 
whole  sensitive  subject. 

The  Objects  of  the  Senses. 

The  Scholastics  distinguish  two  kinds  of  sense  objects, 
essential  and  accidental  ones.  The  first  class  is  again  divided 
into  proper  and  common  sense  objects.  By  an  essential 
sense  object  they  mean  one  which  is  in  fact  presented  to, 
and  grasped  by,  the  sense  or  senses  in  question,  as  distin- 
guished from  an  accidental  object  which  is  not  in  fact  grasped 
by  a  sense,  but  being  known  by  some  other  faculty,  an* 
accompanying  the  essential  sense  object,  is  known  by  the 


234         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

subject  along  with  it.  Thus  bodily  substance  is  an  accidental 
sense  object ;  for,  though  it  is  not  known  by  any  of  the 
senses — it  cannot  be  seen,  or  heard,  or  touched,  and  so  on — 
but  only  by  the  intellect ;  yet,  since  it  goes  along  with  what 
is  sensed  in  itself  or  essentially,  viz.  bodily  accidents,  it  is 
said  to  be  accidentally  sensible.  The  class  of  essential 
sensibles  called  proper  are  those  which  are  the  immediate 
objects  of  any  sense,  which  specify  it,  and  so  are  grasped 
only  by  that  sense  and  no  other,  while  common  sense 
objects  are  those  which  are  mediate  objects  of  any  sense, 
and  are  often  grasped  by  more  than  one  sense. 

Such  mediate  sensibles  are,  however,  of  two  kinds  :  those 
which  are  known  in  themselves  through  some  medium,  and 
those  which  are  not  known  in  themselves,  but  in  some 
representation  or  image  of  themselves.  To  make  clear  what 
is  meant  by  this  we  might  use  the  example  of  the  telescope. 
In  the  usual  form  of  telescope  the  star  is  seen  directly,  and  in 
itself,  though  only  by  the  medium  of  the  instrument ; 
whereas  in  the  reflecting  telescope,  what  is  seen  is  an  image 
or  reflection  of  the  star,  not  the  star  itself,  the  medium  of 
seeing  this  image  being  the  instrument ;  and  that  of  seeing 
the  star  its  reflection  in  the  mirror  of  the  telescope.  The  first 
class  of  immediate  sensibles,  viz.  those  which  are  mediately 
sensed  in  themselves,  are  quantity  and  things  connected 
with  it,  viz.  motion,  rest,  shape,  and  position.  These  are 
presented  to  the  sense  by  means  of  something  else,  e.g. 
colour,  but  nevertheless  they  are  presented  as  they  are  in 
themselves.  Shape  cannot  be  seen  without  colour,  but  never- 
theless the  shape  of  a  coloured  object  is  seen,  is  grasped  by 
the  sense  of  sight. 

The  second  class  of  mediate  sensibles  are  very  different  from 
these,  for  what  is  grasped  by  the  sense  here  is  not  any  sense 
object,  as  it  is  in  itself,  but  as  it  is  in  some  image  or  reflection 
of  itself.  This  reflection  which  represents  the  object  as  it  is 
in  itself,  more  or  less  accurately,  is  to  be  found  in  all  sense 
perceptions,  since  there  is  always  one  essential  sense  object 
which  is  immediately  sensed,  and  is  within  the  organ  of  sense, 
in  immediate  contact  with  the  nerve  endings,  as  e.g.  the 
retinal  image,  or  rather  the  extended  coloured  surface  which 


SENSE   KNOWLEDGE  235 

is  in  immediate  contact  with  the  retina  ;  and  another 
mediate  essential  sense  object,  viz.  the  object  from  which 
this  extended  coloured  surface  is  transmitted,  i.e.  the  ex- 
ternal object.  This  last  is  known  only  by  the  mediation  of 
the  internal  object. 

Simple  sensation  does  not  distinguish  between  the  object 
as  it  is  outside  the  subject,  and  the  object  as  it  is  within  it. 
Both  are  known  by  it,  but  confusedly,  the  internal  object  not 
being  known  as  internal,  nor  the  external  as  external.  This 
is  clear,  since  we  do  not  see  an  object  as  being  in  our  eye,  nor 
hear  a  sound  as  the  vibration  of  that  part  of  the  air  which  is 
in  immediate  contact  with  the  basilar  membrane  of  the  ear, 
though  scientific  investigation  shows  that  these  internal 
objects  are  present,  and  that  it  is  only  by  their  means  that 
we  see  or  hear  the  external  ones.  Consequently  the  external 
object  is  not  known  to  be  external  by  means  of  sensation 
alone  ;  it  is  not  an  essential  sensible,  but  only  an  accidental 
one.  We  conclude  that  it  is  external  by  repeated  observa- 
tions and  comparison  of  different  sense  experiences,  and  so 
may  be  said  to  perceive  its  externality,  though  we  cannot  sense 
that  it  is  external.  The  external  object,  then,  considered  from 
different  points  of  view,  can  be  said  to  be  either  an  essential 
sensible,  or  not  an  essential  sensible,  but  an  accidental  one. 
In  itself,  simply  as  coloured,  round,  etc.,  it  is  an  essential 
sensible,  though  a  mediate  one  known  in  its  intra-organic 
representation  ;  but  in  so  far  as  it  is  external  it  is  not  an 
essential  sensible  at  all.  Consequently,  as  it  is,  if  considered 
absolutely  in  itself,  without  relation  to  the  internal  sense 
impressions  which  it  produces,  or  even  considered  precisely 
as  the  source  of  the  whole  complex  of  such  impressions,  the 
external  object  is  an  accidental  sense  object  which  comes  to 
be  known  gradually  by  putting  together  and  comparing  a 
large  number  of  sense  experiences.  In  this  process  imagina- 
tion and,  in  the  case  of  man,  intellect  play  a  large  part ;  and 
thus  the  way  is  laid  open  to  numerous  mistakes  and  illusions.1 

From  what  we  have  said  it  will  be  clear  that  what  any  sense 

1  The  theory  here  sketched  with  regard  to  mediate  sensibles  is  derived 
from  Fr.  Jos.  Gredt,  O.S.B.  See  his  De  Cognitione  Sensuum  Exlernorum, 
ed^  2a  Romae,  1924.  This  essay  can  also  be  usefully  consulted  for  the 
analysis  of  the  objects  of  each  of  the  senses  in  particular. 


-236         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

perceives  immediately,  and  essentially,  is  the  proper  sense 
object  which  is  internal  to  the  organ  of  the  sense  in  question. 
Thus  the  sight,  e.g.  senses  the  coloration  of  the  ether  which 
is  in  immediate  contact  with  the  retina  :  it  does  not  sense 
essentially,  and  in  itself,  the  object  from  which  this  im- 
pression is  derived,  nor  yet  the  retinal  image  produced  by 
the  '  internal '  object.  This  explains  why  it  is  that  though 
the  retinal  image  is  inverted  the  object  is  not  seen  as 
inverted,  a  fact  which  is  generally  explained  by  saying  that 
custom  enables  us  to  '  rectify  '  the  inversion  of  the  retinal 
image,  interpreting  it,  by  the  imagination,  as  direct.  But  if 
what  is  seen  is  not  the_  physical  (or  photo-chemical) 
impression  on  the  retina,  which  is  certainly  inverted, 
but  the  interior  object  which  represents  the  external 
one,  this  object  will  represent  not  the  position  of  the  rays 
of  light  as  they  are  about  to  fall  on  the  retina,  which  are 
already  refracted,  but  the  position  from  which  the  rays  come, 
and  so  their  direction ;  so  that  the  eye  will  see,  as  coming 
from  above,  what  does  indeed  come  from  above,  and  from 
below,  what  comes  from  below.  This  explanation  will  only 
hold  good  if  the  sensation  of  sight  takes  place  in  the  eye  ; 
whereas  if  it  be  held  that  the  sensation  takes  place  in  the 
brain  this  difficulty  with  regard  to  the  inverted  image  seems 
almost  insoluble,  since  the  brain  can  only  register  what  is 
given  it,  viz.  the  inverted  image  ;  and  cannot  perceive  from 
what  direction  the  light-rays  come  to  fall  on  the  retina,  in 
which  case  the  deliverances  of  the  senses  of  touch  and  sight 
ought  to  be  discordant,  which  is  not  the  case.  This  affords, 
then,  a  confirmation  of  the  view  that  sensation  takes  place 
in  the  sense  organs  and  not  in  the  brain. 

Internal  Sensibility. 

The  Scholastics  usually  partition  the  functions  which  are 
performed  by  the  internal  sensibility  among  four  '  internal 
senses  '  ;  the  common  sense,  imagination,  estimative  faculty 
and  memory  ;  though  Suarez  considers  these  four  to  be  but 
different  functions  of  one  sense. 

The  functions  of  the  common  sense  would  be  those  of 
sensitive  consciousness,   by  which  man  and  the  animals 


SENSE  KNOWLEDGE  237 

would  be  conscious  of  their  sensations,  and  that  of  discrimina- 
tion and  comparison  between  various  sensations,  e.g  of 
sight  and  touch,  by  which  the  subject  is  at  the  moment 
affected. 

Though  traditionally  the  common  sense  has  been  con- 
sidered by  the  Scholastics  to  be  a  separate  faculty  with  a 
special  organ,  it  does  not  seem  clear  that  Aristotle  thought 
it  to  be  other  than  the  general  sensitivity.1  In  fact,  this 
view,  as  Cardinal  Mercier  points  out,2  is  consonant  with  the 
teaching  of  S.  Thomas,  and  avoids  the  considerable  difficul- 
ties which  arise  if  we  regard  the  common  sense  as  a  distinct 
faculty.  Since  the  subject  is  itself  a  unity  it  will  be  able  to 
unify  and  compare  its  own  sensations,  by  means  of  the  sen- 
sitivity which  is  distributed  through  the  whole  organism,  and 
especially  through  the  nervous  system  and  brain.  Another 
function  which  is  exercised  by  the  internal  sensibility  is  that 
of  imagining.  We  know  as  a  fact  of  our  own  experience  that 
sense  perceptions  of  objects  are  often  followed  by  our  making 
representations  of  them  to  ourselves,  picturing  them,  and 
forming  images  of  them.  This  is  the  work  of  the  imagination 
which,  by  means  of  the  formation  of  such  pictures  or  images, 
thereby  enables  the  animal  to  retain  the  knowledge  of 
sensible  objects,  to  know  them  when  absent,  and  to  reproduce 
and  associate  them. 

The  third  function  of  the  internal  sensibility  is  what 
S.  Thomas  called  the  '  estimative  force  '  or  power,  a  function 
which  is  included  under  what  now  goes  by  the  rather  vague 
name  of  '  instinct.'  By  its  means  an  animal  is  able  to 
appreciate  the  beneficial  or  noxious  character  of  the  objects 
of  sense,  and  so  try  to  get  them,  or  avoid  them.  This  power 
arises  from  natural  predispositions  which  are  doubtless 
educated  by  experience.  The  animal  being  by  nature  of  a 
certain  kind  finds  some  things  useful  to  it  and  some  harmful, 
so  that  its  very  nature  moves  it  to  acquire  the  first  and  reject 
the  second.  No  really  satisfactory  explanation  is,  however, 
forthcoming  to  show  how  it  is  that  a  quite  inexperienced 
animal  is  able  to  make  such  discriminations,  as,  e.g.,  to  avoid 

1  Cf.  Ross,  Aristotle,  p.  140. 

2  Mercier,  Psychologie,  Tom.  I,  paragraphs  100  flf. 


238         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

eating  poisonous  or  harmful  herbs.  It  seems  certain  that  any 
satisfactory  explanation  will  have  to  allow  that  the  animal 
has  certain  innate  natural  tendencies  to  definite  ends.  If 
such  tendencies  be  ruled  out,  as  they  must  be  by  any 
mechanistic  account  of  animal  behaviour,  the  fact  of 
instinctive  discrimination  becomes  inexplicable.1 

The  last  function  of  the  internal  sensibility  is  sensitive 
memory  by  means  of  which  the  animal  recognises  past 
experiences  as  past ;  the  memory,  thus  differing  from  the 
imagination,  which  merely  reproduces  them  without  putting 
them  in  their  setting  as  things  experienced  in  the  past.  Such 
recognition  of  past  experiences  is  clear  in  ourselves,  when  we 
recognise  a  face  or  a  place  which  we  have  seen  before,  and  is 
not  to  be  denied  to  the  lower  animals,  who  also  recognise 
persons  and  places  from  which  they  have  been  separated, 
sometimes  for  a  long  time. 

The  Sensitive  Appetite. 

To  complete  our  consideration  of  the  activities  of  sensitive 
nature  we  must  add  something  with  regard  to  its  conative 
capacities,  or,  as  the  Scholastics  call  it,  '  sensitive  appetite.' 
Though  the  word  '  appetite  '  is  used  by  the  Scholastics  to 
signify  any  natural  tendency  which  may  be  found  in  any 
thing,  covering  such  tendencies  as  that  of  heavy  bodies  to 
move  towards  one  another  ;  in  this  connection  its  significa- 
tion is  narrower  and,  excluding  such  innate  or  natural  ten- 
dencies as  those  just  mentioned,  is  confined  to  tendencies 
which  follow  on  cognition.  The  tendencies  which  are  brought 
into  play  by  cognition  may  be  purely  natural  ones,  the  instinc- 
tive tendencies  of  the  animal ;  or  intelligence  may  combine 
with  instinct,  so  that  the  resulting  action  is  spontaneous,  and 
not  dictated  merely  by  the  nature  of  the  subject :  and,  in 
the  case  of  man,  it  is  at  least  theoretically  possible  that  he 
should  desire  what  he  knows  by  his  intellect  to  be  good, 
quite  apart  from  any  impulse  of  his  nature  driving  him  to 
do  so. 

This  notion  of  purposive  tendencies  in  man,  and  a  fortiori 

1  For  a  full  discussion  of  instinct  see  McDougall,  Outline  of  Psychology. 
Esp.  Ch.  IV. 


SENSE   KNOWLEDGE  239 

in  the  lower  animals,  is  altogether  repudiated  and  excluded 
by  modern  psychologists  of  the  materialistic  and  Behaviour- 
istic  schools,  because  it  is  not  observable  by  the  methods  of 
natural  science,  which  can  know  nothing  of  final  causes,  of 
the  '  why  '  of  an  action.  The  success  of  both  biologists  and 
psychologists  in  their  attempt  to  bring  vital  phenomena 
within  the  bounds  imposed  by  itself  on  physical  science  has 
been,  however,  very  incomplete  ;  so  that  in  both  sciences 
there  are  many  authorities  who  wish  to  retain  the  notion  of 
purpose  when  dealing  with  animal  or  human  behaviour,  and 
even  to  make  it  central,  and  the  ruling  principle  of  such 
behaviour  ;  as  does  McDougall,  and  those  associated  with 
him  in  the  Hormic  school. 

It  is,  in  fact,  extraordinarily  difficult  to  deny  the  fact  of 
purpose  in  human  behaviour,  and  even  those  psychologists 
who  do  not  allow  its  existence  devote  all  their  energies  to 
a  definite  purpose  :  the  exclusion  of  purpose.  A  detailed 
examination  of  the  behaviour  of  animals,  in  order  to  deter- 
mine whether  their  actions  can  be  said  to  be  purposive, 
would  require  a  volume  ;  and,  what  is  more  important,  is 
outside  the  scope  of  a  philosophical  investigation  ;  but  both 
common  and  scientific  observation  of  their  actions  shows 
that  it  is  at  least  much  the  simplest  explanation  of  them,  and 
in  fact  the  only  one,  at  present  in  the  field,  which  is  reconcil- 
able with  all  the  known  facts.  From  a  strictly  philosophical 
point  of  view,  moreover,  it  is  certain  that  where  we  have 
cognition  we  must  also  have  appetition  or  conation  ;  so  that 
on  the  supposition  that  the  animals  have  the  former,  they 
must  also  have  the  latter.  The  reason  of  this  statement  is 
that  every  action  must  have  a  definite  efficient  principle 
and  be  directed  towards  some  definite  object  or  end.  For  if 
there  were  no  definite  efficient  principle  of  action  there 
could  be  no  action,  and  if  the  action  had  no  definite  direction 
the  agent  would  not  do  one  thing  rather  than  another,  and 
so  would  not  act  at  all.  The  actions,  moreover,  of  things  are 
governed  by  their  natures  or  forms,  i.e.  they  will  act  in 
accordance  with  their  natures.  Now  the  forms  which  are 
found  in  things  are,  as  we  have  seen,  of  two  kinds,  their 
innate  physical  forms,  and  those  which  they  acquire  through 


240         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

cognition  ;  and  each  of  these  will  direct  their  actions  towards 
a  definite  object  or  end,  so  that  in  both  cases  there  will  be 
an  inclination  or  tendency  which  accompanies  the  possession 
of  these  forms.  In  the  case  of  physical  forms  we  shall  have  a 
uniform,  constant,  and  determined  tendency  towards  a  given 
end  ;  and  in  the  case  of  forms  acquired  by  cognition  a  ten- 
dency towards,  or  away  from,  an  end,  according  as  this  is 
known  as  suitable  or  unsuitable  to  the  agent  in  question. 

We  see,  then,  that  if  we  acknowledge  that  animals  have 
sense  cognition  we  are  also  obliged  to  grant  that  they  have  a 
conative  tendency  which  follows  on  it,  and  is  determined  by 
it,  i.e.  that  they  have  a  sense  appetite.  Whether,  in  fact,  they 
have  such  cognition  is  the  question  which  must  now  be 
discussed. 


CHAPTER  X 

THE    NATURE    OF    THE    LIFE-PRINCIPLE    IN    ANIMALS 

What  We  Mean  by  '  Animal ' — Have  they  Sensation  ? — Opinions  : 
Descartes,  Loeb — The  Thomist  View — Is  Sensation  Peculiar  to 
Animals  ? — The  Life -principle  in  Animals  Essentially  Sensitive, 
and  their  Substantial  Form  :  so  One  Only — Belonging  to  the 
Material  Order,  yet  Specifically  Distinct  from  that  of  Plants — 
Summary. 

As  a  result  of  our  discussion  of  cognition  we  can  now  see  that 
sensation  is  a  cognitive  action,  whose  formal  object  is  the 
individual  material  thing  which  is  presented  to  the  sense, 
and  that  cognitive  action  itself  is  a  metaphysical  one,  by 
which  immaterial  possession  is  taken  of  a  form  ;  the  form  in 
the  case  of  sensation  being,  however,  that  of  an  individual 
material  thing,  and  so  conveniently  called  a  material  form, 
in  contrast  to  those  which  are  altogether  denuded  of  matter, 
either  owing  to  their  nature,  as  spiritual  beings  would  be,  or 
through  the  operation  of  mind  which  takes  away  all  materi- 
ality, and  consequently  all  individuality  from  them. 

If  we  are  to  ask  whether  animals  are  capable  of  sensation, 
and  if  so  whether  they  differ  from  the  plants  in  this  respect, 
we  must  have  a  clear  idea  of  what  we  mean  by  an  animal  as 
distinguished  from  a  plant.  Though  everyone  has  a  vague 
notion  of  what  constitutes  an  animal,  it  would  often  be 
found,  on  examination,  to  be  that  an  animal  is  a  living  being 
which  has  senses,  as  opposed  to  a  plant,  which  has  none. 
Such  a  notion,  if  it  were  employed  here,  would  evidently  lead 
us  in  a  vicious  circle,  for  this  is  precisely  the  question  we  are 
enquiring  into  :  whether  animals  do  indeed  possess  this 
peculiar  power  which  is  not  shared  by  beings  lower  in  the 
vital  scale.  It  is  obvious  that  this  preliminary  notion  which 
we  may  have  of  an  animal  cannot  be  its  essential  definition — 
its  real  definition — since  if  we  return  an  affirmative  answer 

241 


242         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSPOHY 

to  this  question  it  will  be  equivalent  to  saying  that  the 
specific  difference  of  animal  nature  is  sensibility,  so  that  we 
must  be  content,  at  this  stage,  with  a  nominal  and  descrip- 
tive definition  which  may  leave  a  certain  amount  of  doubt  as 
to  whether  some  particular  organisms  are  to  be  considered  as 
animals  or  plants.  The  difficulty  is  paralleled  by  that  which 
we  experience  when  we  ask  whether  rationality  is  the  pre- 
rogative of  man  ;  for  here  again  we  must  take  such  outwaid 
characteristics  as  taillessness,  erect  walk,  articulation  of 
limbs,  brain-structure,  and  so  on,  to  indicate  what  we  mean 
by  man,  and  so  find  it  difficult  to  decide  whether  certain 
fossil  remains  are  human  or  not.  We  must  notice  that  two 
questions  are  included  in  the  one  stated  above,  viz.  (i) 
whether  animals  are  capable  of  sensation,  i.e.  whether  any 
of  those  beings  which  we  agree  to  call  animals  are  capable  of 
it,  and  here  the  difficulty  just  mentioned  does  not  arise,  and 
(2)  whether  all  animals,  and  they  alone,  are  capable  of  it, 
where  the  lack  of  precision  in  our  descriptive  definition  of 
'  animal '  is  bound  to  result  in  a  certain  amount  of  doubtful- 
ness and  obscurity.  We  can  say,  for  certain,  that  capacity 
for  sensation  constitutes  a  specific  difference  or  difference  in 
kind  between  those  beings  which  have  it  and  those  which  do 
not,  though  we  may  find  it  difficult  to  determine  precisely 
where  the  line  of  demarcation  is  to  be  drawn. 

Let  us  first  see  what  sort  of  nominal,  or  descriptive 
definition  we  can  give  of  '  animal.'  From  a  physico-chemical 
point  of  view,  animals  may  be  said  to  be  distinguished  from 
green  plants  by  the  tendency  of  the  processes  of  energy- 
transformation  which  go  on  in  them.  The  tendency  of  the 
green  plant  is  to  accumulate  energy  in  the  form  of  high 
potential  compounds,  such  as  carbo-hydrates,  proteid,  fat  and 
oil,  while  in  the  animal  body  the  tendency  is  to  break  down 
these  compounds  into  water,  carbonic  acid,  urea  and  other 
nitrogenous  substances.  Thus  the  metabolic  action  in  the 
animal  is  destructive,  in  the  plant  constructive. 

A  more  obvious,  as  well  as  a  more  essential,  characteristic* 
which  is  to  be  observed  in  animals,  as  contrasted  with  green 
plants,  is  mobility,  and  mobility  which  is,  at  least  in  appear- 
ance, purposive.    Not  only  is  the  mobility  of  animals  much 


LIFE-PRINCIPLE  IN  ANIMALS  243 

more  extensive  than  that  of  plants,  but  the  typical  animal 
moves  as  a  whole,  while  the  typical  plant  only  moves  its 
parts,  such  as  leaves,  roots  or  tendrils,  and  these  merely  by 
reflex  motions  responding  to  some  external  stimulus.  The 
variety  of  animal  movements  is  also  much  greater  than  that 
of  the  plant.  This  capacity  for  movement  is  due  to  the 
structure  of  the  animal  as  contrasted  with  the  plant,  for  the 
former  possesses  a  sensori-motor  system  which  the  latter 
does  not.  This  system  is  the  skeleton  and  muscles  whereby  the 
animal  is  enabled  to  move  from  place  to  place,  to  seize  its 
food,  and  so  on,  and  to  masticate  it,  as  well  as  the  peripheral 
sensory  and  motor  nerves,  and  the  central  nervous  system 
and  brain.  No  doubt  the  plain  man  would  say  of  a  creature 
that  was  observed  to  move  itself  from  place  to  place  that  it 
was  an  animal  and  not  a  plant ;  and  though  this  charac- 
teristic, by  itself,  is  not  for  us  a  sufficient  indication  of  the 
nature  of  an  organism,  it  occupies,  no  doubt,  an  important 
place  in  the  characteristic  behaviour  of  the  typical  animal. 
As  animal  life  progresses  the  sensori-motor  system  becomes 
more  developed  and  the  animal  grows  more  and  more  mobile. 
According  to  these  indications,  then,  it  will  be  sufficient  for 
our  present  purpose  to  describe  an  animal  as  a  living  being 
whose  characteristic  metabolic  tendency  is  analytic,  and 
which  is  mobile,  its  mobility  being  due  to  the  possession  of  a 
sensori-motor  system. 

We  can  now  ask  whether  those  beings  which  possess  a 
combination  of  these  characteristics  are  capable  of  sensation, 
while  those  which  do  not  possess  it,  are  not.  We  remarked 
that  the  capacity  for  sensation  must  constitute  a  specific 
difference,  and  the  truth  of  this  statement  appears  if  we 
consider  that  sensation  implies  a  degree  of  immateriality 
in  its  possessor  which  is  not  found  in  an  insensitive 
being. 

Such  a  surplus  of  immateriality  is  a  positive  addition  to 
the  being  of  a  thing,  and  so  is  an  element  of  being,  found  in  it 
over  and  above  that  which  is  found  in  other  entities.  Evid- 
ently nothing  more  than  additional  being  can  be  required  to 
constitute  specific  difference,  since  there  is  nothing  more 
than  being,  so  that  where  we  find  a  positive  addition  of  being, 


244         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

as  in  this  case,  we  can  affirm  that  we  are  in  the  presence  of  a 
specific  difference. 

Our  first  question,  whether  any  animals,  using  the  word 
animal  in  the  sense  indicated  above,  are  capable  of  sensation, 
is  one  to  which  common  sense  readily  gives  an  affirmative 
answer  ;  nevertheless,  a  negative  one  has  often  been  given  by 
philosophers.  It  must,  of  course,  be  denied  that  animals 
sense,  by  the  materialists  and  those  who  deny  that  there  is 
any  distinction,  except  that  of  the  degree  of  its  complexity, 
between  organic  and  inorganic  matter.  Their  view  on  this 
point  is  clearly  but  a  corollary  of  their  general  position,  and 
we  have  already  seen  that  it  is  impossible  to  maintain  that 
living  things  are  a  mere  compound  of  matter  and  its  forces. 

There  are,  however,  others  who  while  not  denying  the  dis- 
tinction between  animate  and  inanimate  things,  nevertheless, 
will  not  allow  that  the  animals  sense.  Of  these  the  first  is 
Descartes,  who  divided  beings  into  two  classes,  those  which 
are  constituted  by  geometrical  extension,  and  those  which 
are  endowed  with  thought.  Since  he  held  that  the  animals 
are  not  capable  of  thought,  as  a  consequence  he  had  to 
include  them  in  his  first  class,  and  say  that  they  are  purely 
material  constructions,  inanimate  and  insensible.  So  he 
says  :  '  The  animals  act  naturally  by  springs,  like  a  watch.' 
He  imagined  that  the  more  rarefied  parts  of  the  blood 
ascended  to  the  brain,  and  there,  in  the  ventricles,  became 
what  he  called  '  the  animal  spirits  ' ;  a  kind  of  fluid  contained 
in  them,  whose  flow  was  regulated  by  valves  in  the  nerves, 
which  he  thought  of  as  fine  tubes.  On  the  stimulation  of  the 
surface  of  the  body,  threads  in  the  nerves  were  pulled  by  it 
opening  the  valves,  and  allowing  the  animal  spirits  to  flow 
along  them,  thus  causing  contraction,  etc.,  of  the  muscles, 
motion,  and  the  other  phenomena  of  what  we  call  life. 
Though  this  theory,  with  the  growth  of  physiological  know- 
ledge, had  to  be  abandoned  altogether,  the  underlying  notion 
that  the  motions  of  animals  are  to  be  explained  merely 
mechanically  has  survived,  and  has  been  embodied  in  theories 
such  as  that  of  Loeb.  This  is  known  as  the  theory  of 
'  tropisms  '  ;  which  in  its  generalised  form  ascribes  all  the 
motions  of  animals  to  physico-chemical  responses  or  reactions 


LIFE-PRINCIPLE   IN  ANIMALS  245 

to  external  stimuli,  such  as  light.  So,  for  example,  the 
motions  of  a  caterpillar  which  moves  up  a  plant  and  eats  the 
green  shoots  at  the  top  are  explained  by  saying  that,  if  at 
the  beginning  of  the  movement,  the  body  of  the  caterpillar 
is  at  an  angle  to  the  direction  of  the  light  rays  (in  this  case 
the  sun's  rays),  one  side  of  its  body  will  be  more  illuminated 
than  the  other.  This  will  cause  the  muscles  on  that  side  to 
contract,  and  so  the  caterpillar  will  be  turned  round  towards 
the  rays,  and  when  its  body  is  in  line  with  their  direction, 
both  sides  of  it  will  be  equally  stimulated,  and  contracting 
equally,  will  cause  it  to  move  towards  the  light.  This  posi- 
tion will  clearly  be  one  of  stable  equilibrium,  since  on  any 
divergence  from  it  the  unequal  stimulation  of  the  sides  of  its 
body  will  cause  it  to  resume  it.  Such  an  organism  is  said  to 
be  positively  heliotropic,  or  positively  phototropic.  Move- 
ments away  from  a  source  of  light  are  explained  in  a  similar 
way.  Though,  in  fact,  the  hypothesis  was  only  successful  in 
explaining  some  parts  of  the  movements  of  some  of  the 
lowest  organisms,  it  was  hoped  that  with  increased  know- 
ledge it  might  be  made  to  cover  all  movements  of  all  organ- 
isms ;  a  pious  hope  whose  realisation  is  becoming  continually 
less  probable,  as  new  facts  become  known  which  cannot  be 
forced  within  the  limits  of  the  theory.1  Though,  then,  it 
may  be  true  that  tropism  plays  a  part  in  directing  the 
motions  of  animals,  it  cannot  be  considered  to  be  an  all- 
sufficient  explanation  of  them.  According  to  Professor 
J.  S.  Haldane,  the  mechanistic  theory  of  life  is  now  '  bank- 
rupt,' and  physiologists  have  lost  interest  in  it  ;2  but 
whatever  be  the  prevailing  opinion  of  scientists  with  regard 
to  it,  the  following  considerations  are  sufficient  to  show  it  to 
be  untrue  in  its  application  to  the  animals.  For,  in  the  first 
place,  'the  variety  of  the  motions  of  animals  shows  that  they 
do  not  move  merely  in  response  to  physico-chemical  stimuli, 
since  they  change  their  motions  and  cease  from  action  even 
though  the  stimuli  remain  constant.  Further,  they  do  not 
always  respond  in  the  same  way  to  the  same  stimuli ;   and 

1  Cf.  McDougall,  Outline  of  Psychology,  pp.  62  ff.     Johnstone,   The 
Philosophy  of  Biology,  pp.  148  ff. 

2  J.  S.  Haldane,  The  Sciences  and  Philosophy,  p.  57,  and  the  whole  of 
Lect.  3. 


246         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

very  different  stimuli  often  produce  the  same  response. 
Moreover,  they  adapt  themselves  to  the  situation  in  which 
they  are  placed  in  a  way  which  mechanisms  cannot  do,  as 
Professor  Haldane  shows  with  respect  to  breathing  in  a  pro- 
gressively rarefied  atmosphere.1  Add  to  this,  that  if  we 
grant,  as  we  can  hardly  refuse  to  do  in  the  face  of  our  own 
experience,  that  we  have  sensible  cognition,  we  cannot  deny 
it  to  the  animals,  since  they  display  signs  of  emotion  similar 
to  those  which  we  observe  in  ourselves,  exhibiting  in  various 
ways  marks  of  pleasure,  affection,  anger,  fear,  and  so  on.  It 
is  also  difficult  to  deny  that  they  desire  and  go  in  search  of 
food,  drink,  and  other  bodily  gratifications  if  we  allow  that 
men  do,  since  their  mode  of  behaviour  is  precisely  similar  to 
our  own.  No  one  can  refuse  to  admit  that  many  animals 
have  all  the  sense-organs  which  we  ourselves  possess,  and  all 
of  them  at  least  some  of  these  organs.  If,  then,  we  admit 
that  we  have  sense  cognition  by  means  of  these  organs,  we 
can  hardly  deny  such  cognition  to  the  other  animals, 
especially  in  view  of  their  behaviour  and  use  of  these  organs. 
All  these  considerations,  at  any  rate  if  taken  together,  ought 
to  be  sufficient  to  convince  us  that  the  animals  are  indeed 
capable  of  sense-knowledge,  and  are  not  to  be  considered  as 
mere  automata  or  machines.  Are  we,  however,  to  regard 
this  capacity  as  the  peculiar  prerogative  of  animals,  or 
should  it  be  extended  to  all  living  organisms  ?  Those  who 
think  that  it  should  are  chiefly  influenced  by  the  fact  that 
we  find  no  absolutely  sharp  line  of  demarcation  either  in 
structure  or  behaviour  between  the  lowest  forms  of  animal 
life  and  the  highest  forms  of  what  are  recognised  as  plants. 
Thus  it  is  stated  that '  some  lower  organisms,  the  Peridinians 
and  the  Algal  spores,  exhibit  all  the  characters  which  we 
utilise  in  separating  animals  from  plants.'2  Apart  from  the 
fact  that  this  statement  seems  somewhat  exaggerated,  since 
it  is  acknowledged  that  they  possess  but  the  rudiments  of 
a  sensori-motor  system,  if  it  be  regarded  as  such  at  all,  and 
other  animal  characteristics,  if  at  all,  only  in  a  very  elemen- 
tary form  ;  it  is  surely  a  fallacious  method  of  argument. 
What  is  shown  by  the  facts  is  merely  that  there  are  some 

1  Haldane,  op.  cit.,  p.  94.  2  Johnstone,  op.  cit.,  p.  201. 


LIFE-PRINCIPLE  IN  ANIMALS  247 

organisms  about  which  we  cannot  be  certain  whether  they 
are  to  be  reckoned  as  plants  or  animals  ;  not,  as  is  assumed, 
that  we  must  attribute  to  some  plants,  and  then,  by  an  added 
assumption,  to  all  plants,  the  essential  characteristics  which 
are  found  in  acknowledged  animals.  From  the  point  of  view 
of  philosophy  it  is  of  no  consequence  to  decide  what  particular 
organisms  are  to  be  reckoned  as  plants  and  what  as  animals, 
the  only  question  is  whether  some  organisms  must  be  held 
to  be  capable  of  cognition,  while  others  cannot  be  said  to  be 
capable  of  it  :  for  this,  if  it  is  the  case,  will  establish  the  fact 
that  there  is  a  specific  difference  among  organisms.  No 
doubt  the  gradual  fading,  as  it  were,  of  the  animal  world  into 
the  vegetable,  makes  us  suspect  that  plants  differ  only  in 
degree,  and  not  in  kind,  from  the  animals  ;  but  we  ought  to 
base  our  theories  on  facts,  not  our  facts  on  theories.  We 
ought  to  say  that  since  we  see  clear  indications  of  sensation 
in  almost  all  the  organisms  we  class  as  animal,  and  no  such 
indications  in  almost  all  those  we  class  as  vegetable,  it  is 
present  in  the  one  class  and  not  in  the  other  ;  and  not  that 
since  we  think  it  may  be  present  in  a  few  examples  of  plant 
life,  it  must  be  present  in  all,  even  though  observation  lends 
no  support  to  such  a  view.  Probably  the  chief  ground  for 
making  such  an  assertion  is  an  unacknowledged  prejudice,  or 
belief,  that  in  fact  all  living  things  have  been  evolved  from 
simple  protoplasm  and  therefore  life  must  be  essentially  the 
same  whether  it  be  that  of  a  man  or  an  acorn.  Such  a  falla- 
cious a  priori  way  of  arguing  might  be  excusable  in  a  philo- 
sopher during  the  decadence  of  Scholasticism  ;  but  is  much 
less  so  in  the  scientist  in  an  age  of  positivism  and  enlighten- 
ment. Further,  it  is  not  by  any  means  clear  that  the  facts 
which  are  supposed  to  lend  their  support  to  this  theory 
really  do  so.  It  is  true  that  in  what  we  may  call '  boundary- 
forms  '  we  may  find,  on  what  is  reckoned  as  the  animal  side, 
some  energy-transformations  which  are  of  the  same  kind  as 
those  typical  of  plants,  viz.  synthetic  ones,  while  analytic 
transformations  are  found  among  organisms  reckoned  as 
vegetables  ;  yet  the  main  tendency  in  the  first  is  analytic, 
and  in  the  second  synthetic.  Again,  though  motility  is 
found  in  some   plants,   as  we  have  noticed,  yet  it  is  so 


248         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

undirected  and  random,  so  lacking  in  any  appearance  of 
spontaneity  or  purpose,  that  it  looks  much  more  like  a  tropism 
than  a  sensitive  reaction  to  felt  stimuli,  whereas  the  motions 
of  even  the  unicellular  animalcule,  such  as  Paramcecium, 
exhibit  fairly  clear  signs  of  conscious  and  spontaneous  action. 
So,  on  coming  in  contact  with  a  solid  object,  it  usually 
reverses  its  motion  and  backs  away  from  it,  then  turning 
slightly  swims  towards  it  again,  and  lastly  remains  quiescent; 
all  without  any  change  in  the  external  stimuli ;  so  that  the 
changes  in  its  movements  must  be  ascribed  to  something 
within  the  animalcule,  viz.  its  consciousness  or  sensitivity. 
So  it  does  not  seem  possible  to  explain  all  its  movements  in 
terms  of  reflexes  or  tropisms,1  as  apparently  can  be  done  in 
the  case  of  Algal  Zoospores.  If  all  this  is  even  approximately 
true,  it  seems  that  the  nature  of  these  organisms  is  too 
obscure  to  justify  us  in  using  our  view  of  it  as  a  basis  for 
asserting  that  all  plant  and  animal  life  is  of  the  same  kind, 
in  face  of  the  clear  evidences  of  sensitivity  which  are  mani- 
fested by  the  majority  of  animals,  and  the  absence  of  any 
such  evidences  in  the  majority  of  plants. 

We  can  conclude,  then,  with  a  fair  degree  of  confidence, 
that  animals  are  possessed  of  sensitive  life,  which  is  their 
own  peculiar  prerogative,  so  that  cognition  being  found  in 
the  animal  world  and  not  in  the  vegetable,  these  two  differ 
specifically,  or  in  kind. 

Two  corollaries  follow  from  this  :  first,  that  the  animals 
are  animated  by  a  principle  of  life  which  is  sensitive,  since 
there  must  be  a  source  of  their  sensitive  operations  which  is 
of  the  same  kind  as  these  ;  and,  secondly,  that  this  life- 
principle  is  their  substantial  form,  since,  their  specific 
difference  being  sensitivity,  that  which  makes  them  sensitive 
beings  will  be  that  which  constitutes  their  nature  specifically: 
that  is  to  say,  their  substantial  form  ;  and  it  is  clear  that  it 
is  their  sensitive  life-principle  which  makes  them  sensitive 
beings,  and  is  therefore  their  substantial  form. 

It  is  hardly  necessary  to  emphasise  again,  what  has  been 

1  H.  S.  Jennings,  The  Behaviour  of  the  Lower  Organisms,  pp.  23  fif.,  who 
concludes,  from  his  observations,  that  '  the  behaviour  of  Amoeba  is 
directly  adaptive,'  and  that  its  '  behaviour  is  not  purely  reflex.' 


LIFE-PRINCIPLE  IN  ANIMALS  249 

said  so  often  already,  that  substantial  form  can  be  one  only  ; 
but  applying  this  truth  to  the  case  in  question,  we  see  that 
the  animals  cannot  have  two  life-principles,  one  vegetative 
and  the  other  sensitive,  but  only  one,  which  is  formally 
sensitive  and  virtually  vegetative,  i.e.  one  which  can  cause 
those  effects  which  would  proceed  from  a  vegetative  one 
were  it  present.  Further,  since  it  is  formally  sensitive,  it  is 
of  its  nature  occupied  only  with  material  objects  and 
material  operations  ;  in  other  words,  its  operations  are 
essentially  dependent  on  matter,  and  it  itself  is  not  spiritual, 
but  belongs  to  the  material  order  ;  for  we  are  bound  to  judge 
of  the  nature  of  a  thing  from  the  consideration  of  its  essential 
operations.  If,  then,  it  is  dependent  on  matter  both  for  its 
operation  and  its  very  being,  it  will  be  generated  from 
matter,  and,  on  the  corruption  of  the  compound  of  which 
it  is  the  form,  will  cease  to  be  actually ;  and  so  is  not 
immortal. 

Such,  then,  are  the  general  conclusions  which  we  can  come 
to  as  to  the  nature  of  animals.  Just  as  even  the  lowliest  of 
living  things  in  the  realm  of  plants  are  superior  to,  and 
specifically  distinct  from,  all  inanimate  things,  being  capable 
of  immanent  action,  and  so  having  an  actuality  and 
immateriality  which  is  not  found  in  the  inorganic  realm  ;  so 
also  the  animals  are  superior  to,  and  differ  in  kind  from,  the 
plants  ;  being  possessed  of  that  immateriality  which  is 
implied  by  cognition  ;  and  so  of  a  positive  perfection  over 
and  above  those  found  in  the  lower  realm.  At  the  same  time, 
their  life  is  still  altogether  dependent  on  matter ;  and  they 
cannot  be  called  spiritual,  but  must  be  reckoned  as  belonging 
to  the  material  order.  We  are  now  to  ascend  one  step 
further  in  the  scale  of  living  beings,  and  consider  those 
which  seem  to  bridge  the  gap,  as  it  were,  between  the 
material  and  the  spiritual,  viz.  men. 

Before  doing  so,  it  may  be  well  to  pause,  and  look  back 
over  our  account  of  the  life  of  plant  and  animal ;  and  to 
synthetise  our  notions  of  the  life-principle  in  these  realms, 
since  the  Thomistic  idea  of  the  '  souls  '  of  plants  and  animals 
has  been  so  often  misconceived.  We  are  unable  to  agree 
either  with  the  materialistic  and  mechanistic  view  of  life, 


250         MODERN   THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

which  represents  it  as  simply  the  sum  total  of  the  physico- 
chemical  forces  of  which  the  body  is  made  up,  or  with  that 
of  the  vitalists,  such  as  Stahl,  who  imagined  that  there  was 
in  the  living  body  some  energy-producing  force,  or  forces, 
over  and  above,  and  independent  of,  the  physico-chemical 
ones  which  are  present  in  it.  The  '  soul,'  in  S.  Thomas' 
view,  is  not  a  thing  or  entity  on  its  own  account,  but  the 
directing,  co-ordinating,  unifying  principle  of  the  whole 
organism,  whereby  this  organism  acts  immanently  and  as  a 
whole.  The  action  of  this  principle  in  no  way  affects  the 
total  energy  of  the  organism,  but  merely  directs  it  in  a 
particular  way.  Just  as  a  workman  with  a  pile  of  bricks 
expends  the  same  amount  of  physical  energy  whether  he 
piles  them  in  a  disorderly  heap,  or  builds  a  house  with  them, 
so  the  energy  of  an  organic  system  remains  the  same  whether 
the  physical  forces  in  it  act  independently,  and  at  random, 
or  are  directed  in  a  definite  fashion,  and  co-ordinated  by 
this  vital  principle.  Further,  though  this  '  soul '  belongs  to 
the  material  order,  as  contrasted  with  the  spiritual  one  ; 
being  dependent  for  its  very  existence  on  the  matter  which 
it  informs,  it  is,  nevertheless,  not  in  itself  endowed  with  the 
properties  of  matter,  not  being  in  itself  spatially  extended, 
though  it  acts  in  space  ;  and  not  being  a  source  of  physico- 
chemical  energy,  though  it  directs  it. 


DIVISION  IV.     INTELLECTUAL  LIFE 

We  are  now  to  investigate  the  third  and  highest  grade 
of  life,  namely,  human  life.  The  most  striking  difference 
between  man  and  the  other  animals  is,  no  doubt,  the  pos- 
session by  the  former  of  intellectual  powers  ;  so  that  our 
primary  business  will  be  to  enquire  into  the  nature  of  these 
powers  ;  first,  with  regard  to  their  generic  nature  :  to 
determine  whether  they  are  organic  or  not ;  secondly,  with 
regard  to  their  specific  nature,  which  is  the  question  concern- 
ing the  object  of  the  intellect  ;  and,  lastly,  to  ask  how  the 
intellect  comes  to  know  its  objects  ;  the  question  of  the  pro- 
cess of  intellectual  knowledge,  or  of  the  origin  of  ideas. 

In  treating  of  these  questions  here,  in  the  philosophy  of 
nature,  we  shall  use  the  same  methods  as  those  employed  in 
dealing  with  the  ones  which  we  have  already  discussed  ;  that 
is  to  say,  direct  methods  of  observation,  both  of  other  men, 
and  more  especially,  since  we  ourselves  are  men,  of  our  own 
mental  processes,  by  introspection.  The  question  whether 
the  results  of  such  observations  are  valid,  or  whether  we  are 
led  astray  by  deceptive  appearances,  is  one  which  is  outside 
the  limits  of  our  present  enquiry ;  since  it  can  only  be 
answered,  if  at  all,  by  means  of  a  reflective  analysis  of  our 
knowledge  ;  and  so  is  dealt  with  in  Epistemology,  whose  aim 
is  to  investigate  the  nature  of  our  knowledge  by  means  of 
reflection.  Thus  questions  as  to  the  nature  of  universal 
concepts,  and  so  on,  are  left  over  to  a  later  stage.  This  being 
understood,  we  can  now  proceed  to  ask  what  the  nature  of 
intellectual  life  appears  to  be. 


251 


CHAPTER  XI 

THE   NATURE   OF  THE   INTELLECT 

Views  as  to  its  Immateriality — S.  Thomas'  Primary  Reason  for 
Holding  it  to  be  So — Its  Objects  :  Common  Formal  Object, 
and  Proper  Formal  Object — Further  Reasons  for  Regarding 
the  Intellect  as  Immaterial — The  Question  of  Its  Activity — 
Our  Knowledge  of  Individuals. 

We  have  seen  that  the  root  of  cognition  is  immateriality,  so 
that  a  thing  which  is  wholly  and  purely  material  can  have 
no  knowledge  ;  and  since  it  is  undisputed  that  the  intellect  is 
a  cognitive  faculty,  it  follows  that  it  must  be  to  some  extent 
immaterial.  What,  then,  is  the  extent  of  its  immateriality  ? 
Is  it  like  the  senses,  which  are  organic,  being  dependent  on 
the  organism  both  for  their  existence  and  their  action,  or,  if 
not,  is  it  entirely  independent  of  the  organism  ?  To  be  so  it 
would  have  to  be  independent  of  it  both  subjectively  and 
objectively,  that  is  to  say,  it  would  have  to  be  capable  of 
existing  independently  of  the  organism,  and  also  able  to 
acquire  its  knowledge  of  objects  without  its  aid. 

The  question  whether  it  can  do  this  last,  or  not,  can  only 
be  answered  when  it  is  known  what  these  objects  are,  a 
subject  which  is  to  be  discussed  later,  so  that  here  we  are 
only  concerned  to  discover  whether  it  is  subjectively  indepen- 
dent of  the  organism  or  not.  If  this  were  the  case,  it  would 
neither  contain  matter  as  a  part  of  itself,  nor  be  dependent 
on  it  for  its  existence  and  action  ;  but  having  an  existence 
of  its  own,  and  not  as  an  element  of  a  compound  which 
receives  existence  only  as  a  whole,  would  be  strictly  speaking 
immaterial  or  spiritual. 

It  is  obvious  that  materialism  must  deny  any  immateri- 
ality to  the  intellect,  and,  a  fortiori,  that  it  is  subjectively 
independent  of  the  organism  :  a  denial  which  is  expressed 
plainly,  though  crudely,  in  the  assertion  that  '  the  brain 

252 


THE  NATURE  OF  THE  INTELLECT        253 

secretes  thought  as  the  liver  secretes  bile.'  A  more  subtle 
form  of  the  same  notion  is  to  be  found  in  the  view  of  the 
Behaviourists  that  thought  actually  consists  of  minute  move- 
ments of  the  larynx  in  forming  sub-vocal  speech.  This 
theory  as  to  the  nature  of  thought  was,  of  course,  devised  to 
bring  it  within  the  general  scheme  as  to  the  character  of  all 
vital  action,  viz.  that  it  is  essentially  a  physico  chemical 
reaction  to  stimuli  of  the  same  kind.  Since  we  have  already 
tried  to  show  that  vital  action  cannot  be  of  this  sort,  we 
must  omit  any  special  criticism  of  this  theory  of  thought, 
and  resist  the  temptation  to  point  out  its  inconsistencies. 
The  English  Empiricists,  as  Hume  and  the  Associationists, 
carrying  to  its  logical  conclusion  the  movement  begun  by 
Locke,  considered  that  intellectual  thought  is  a  combination 
of  particular  sense-images,  and  so  implies  no  more  spiritu- 
ality in  its  possession  than  sensation  does. 

Those  philosophers  who  have  been  in  the  main  stream  of 
philosophic  thought  since  philosophy  first  emerged  from  its 
sources,  beginning  with  Socrates,  Plato,  and  Aristotle,  or 
even  earlier  thinkers,  have  always  consistently  maintained  the 
essentially  immaterial  character  of  the  intellect.  This  tenet  is 
common  to  those  whose  views  in  other  respects  differ  widely  : 
as  S.  Thomas,  Descartes,  Leibniz,  Kant,  Hegel,  and  their 
successors,  as  well  as  the  modern  representatives  of  this 
tradition,  as  Bradley,  Croce,  or  Bergson.  This  conviction, 
so  constant  among  philosophers,  if  not  easily  arrived  at,  yet 
is  one  which  grows  gradually  in  strength  as  each  aspect  of 
our  experience  successively  confirms  it.  That  reality  is 
essentially  immaterial,  and  that  the  human  mind,  as  the 
nearest  approach  to  absolute  reality  of  which  we  have 
immediate  experience,  is  so  also,  are  assertions  which 
become  increasingly  clear  and  certain  as  philosophic  reflec- 
tion continues.  Some  of  the  main  roads  by  which  we  are 
led  to  this  conviction  must  now  be  mapped  out ;  and  it  will 
first  be  well  to  trace  that  one  which  S.  Thomas  seems  to  have 
regarded  as  leading  most  plainly  and  directly  to  this  con- 
clusion.1 

1  Summa  Theologica,  1.75,2  ;  Q.  disp.  de  Anima,  A.  14  ;  Comm.  in  de 
Anima,  Lib.  Ill,  Lect.  7. 


254         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

This  argument  is  derived  from  the  unlimited  scope  of 
intellectual  operations.  It  should  be  clear  from  all  that  has 
been  said  as  to  the  nature  of  knowledge  that  it  is  a  kind  of 
union  between  its  subject  and  object,  whereby  the  knowing 
subject  becomes,  in  a  certain  way,  the  things  which  it  knows, 
while  retaining  its  own  nature.  It  must  therefore  be  capable 
of  becoming  any  of  these,  but  not  be  actually  any  of  them, 
since,  if  it  were,  it  is  clear  that  it  could  not  become  them. 
Thus,  that  the  sense  of  sight  may  know  various  colours  it 
must  be  capable  of  receiving  or  becoming  all  of  them,  but 
cannot  be  any  of  them.  As  a  man  looking  through  blue 
glasses  sees  everything  blue,  so  the  sense  of  sight,  if  it  were 
itself  of  any  determinate  colour,  could  not  know  a  variety 
of  colours.  If  we  now  apply  this  principle  to  the  intellect,  we 
observe  that  there  is  no  corporeal  nature  which  is  incapable 
of  being  known  by  it ;  for,  of  whatever  sort  it  is,  we  certainly 
can  know  it  as  a  thing  or  a  being  of  a  definite  kind  ;  and  it 
therefore  follows,  from  our  principle,  that  the  nature  of  the 
intellect  cannot  be  that  of  any  one  of  the  bodies  which  it  can 
know.  Since,  then,  these  are  all  the  bodies  there  are,  its  nature 
cannot  be  corporeal  or  bodily  at  all,  but  must  be  incorporeal 
or  spiritual.  In  saying  that  the  intellect  can  know  the  nature 
of  any  body,  since  it  can  always  know  it  as  a  being  or  thing 
of  a  determinate  kind,  we  do  not  mean  to  imply  that  it  can 
necessarily  grasp  that  ultimate  specific  difference  whereby  it 
is,  in  the  last  resort,  differentiated  from  all  other  bodies  ; 
but  that  it  can  grasp  it  as  a  thing  which  is  at  least  super- 
ficially or  accidentally  differentiated  from  all  others.  More- 
over, since,  as  we  have  seen,  it  can  know  the  essential 
difference  between  inorganic  and  organic  bodies  ;  and,  again, 
within  the  latter  class,  the  essential  differences  between  plant 
and  animal;  and,  as  we  shall  see  shortly,  between 
animal  and  man  ;  it  can  grasp  the  determinate  nature 
of  all  these  bodies,  and  consequently,  cannot  be  either 
inorganic  or  organic  body  :  either  brute  matter,  plant, 
animal,  or  man.  These  classes,  however,  cover  all  bodies  ; 
so  that  it  cannot  be  any  body.  Notice,  further  :  it  is  said 
that  it  can  know  all  bodies,  not  that  it  actually  does  so  ;  for 
since  its  knowledge  is  derived  from  experience,  and  it  has  no 


THE   NATURE  OF  THE   INTELLECT         255 

intuition  of  the  natures  of  things,  the  process  of  acquiring 
knowledge  of  these  is  a  long  and  arduous  one  ;  but  it  can, 
nevertheless,  absolutely  speaking,  penetrate  beneath  the 
superficial  appearances  to  know  what  is  essential  to  them,  as, 
e.g.,  that  they  are  animals  or  plants.  It  has  been  objected 
that  the  principle  :  '  that  which  knows  any  nature  cannot 
have  that  nature  intrinsically  and  physically  in  itself  '  cannot 
be  maintained  at  the  same  time  as  the  proposition  that  the 
intellect  can  know  being,  since,  in  this  case,  the  intellect 
would  not  have  the  nature  of  being  intrinsically  and  phys- 
ically in  itself,  and  so  would  not  be  being,  i.e.  would  be 
nothing,  which  is  absurd.  Such  an  objection  shows  that  the 
point  of  S.  Thomas'  argument  has  been  missed,  since  the 
nature  of  being  is  not  a  determinate  nature  which  excludes 
others,  but,  on  the  contrary,  an  indeterminate  one  which 
includes  all.  The  whole  point  of  the  argument  is  that  the 
possession  of  a  particular  determinate  corporeal  nature  by  the 
intellect  would  render  it  unable  to  know  things  as  of  a 
different  nature  to  its  own  ;  as  the  sight  knows  all  things  as 
coloured,  never  as  odoriferous  or  resonant — its  own  nature 
preventing  it  from  knowing  these  other  attributes — and 
knows  only  a  certain  very  limited  range  of  colours,  the 
visible  spectrum,  all  others  being  excluded  from  the  range  of 
its  knowledge  owing  to  the  fact  that  the  organ  on  which  it  is 
essentially  dependent  possesses  a  determinate  bodily  nature. 

This  argument,  then,  gives  us  a  solid  ground  for  thinking 
that  the  intellect  is  a  strictly  incorporeal  and  spiritual 
faculty,  and,  moreover,  that  it  cannot  act  by  means  of  any 
bodily  organ,  since,  if  it  did  it  could  only  know  that  deter- 
minate class  of  bodies  which  have  affinity  with  this  organ, 
and  not  all  bodies,  just  as  the  sight  can  know  only  a  deter- 
minate class  of  colours. 

Our  conclusion  that  the  intellect  is  thus  incorporeal 
will  be  strengthened  after  an  examination  of  its  objects, 
which  will  at  the  same  time  tell  us  what  its  specific  nature  is, 
since  faculties  are  specified  by  their  objects,1  and  to  this  we 
now  pass. 

By  '  object '  in  this  context  we  mean  the  formal  object,2 

1  Cf.  Part  II,  Ch.  Ill,  Q.  2,  p.  194.  2  Cf.  p.  195. 


256         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

and  if  we  wish  to  discover  the  nature  of  the  human  intellect, 
as  distinguished  from  any  other,  we  shall  have  to  find  out 
what  its  proper,  as  distinct  from  its  common,  formal  object 
is  ;  for  the  common  formal  object  of  the  intellect  is  that 
which  the  intellect,  as  such,  and  not  some  particular  kind  of 
intellect,  formally  grasps  ;  while  the  proper  formal  object  of 
the  human  intellect  is  that  which  is  formally  known  by  it 
alone.  These  two  are  also  sometimes  known  as  the  adequate 
and  proportionate  objects  of  the  human  intellect.  If,  then, 
we  ask  what  is  the  adequate  or  common  object  of  the  human 
intellect,  as  intellect,  we  see  it  must  be  that  object  outside  of, 
and  apart  from,  which  nothing  can  be  known,  and  which 
includes  all  the  particular  intelligible  objects.  This  object 
must  be  being,  for,  in  the  first  place,  nothing  is  intelligible 
unless  it  is  being  of  some  kind  ;  for  what  is  not  being  is 
nothing,  and  so  not  knowable  ;  since,  to  say  I  know  nothing 
is  equivalent  to  saying  I  do  not  know.  Secondly,  the  only 
object  which  includes  all  particular  objects  of  the  intellect  is 
being  in  general ;  for  every  addition  to  being  limits  it ;  and 
so;  by  such  addition,  being  in  general  is  transformed  into  a 
particular  kind  of  being.  So,  for  instance,  spiritual  being, 
human  being,  and  corporeal  being,  are  classes  formed  by  the 
addition  of  some  quality  to  being  in  general.  From  this  it 
follows  that  since  the  intellect  knows,  or  can  know,  things 
which  are  included  in  all  such  classes  ;  all  its  objects  will 
not  be  included  in  any  one  of  them  ;  some  being  found  in 
one  class  and  some  in  another.  These  classes  of  beings,  more- 
over, agree  in  the  notion  of  being,  and  in  nothing  else.  Hence 
the  objects  of  the  intellect  also,  included  in  these  classes, 
agree  in  the  notion  of  being  only  ;  which  notion,  therefore, 
includes  all  intelligible  objects.  So  every  notion  must 
ultimately  be  resolved  into  the  primary  notion  of  being.1 
If,  e.g.,  we  were  to  ask  :  What  is  man  ?  the  answer  would  be 
rational  animal.  What,  then,  is  an  animal  ?  We  answer  ; 
sensitive  living  substance  ;  and  what  is  substance  ?  a  thing 
or  being  to  whose  nature  is  due  existence  in  itself.  Similarly, 
with  all  other  notions,  analysis  always  leads  us  eventually  to 
the  notion  of  being.   In  the  same  way  every  judgement  has  as 

1  Cf.  S.  Thomas,  De  Veritate,  1,1. 


THE  NATURE  OF  THE  INTELLECT         257 

its  formal  element  the  word  '  is/  whereby  identity  of  being 
between  the  subject  and  predicate  is  affirmed  ;  and  every 
argument  assigns  from  the  premisses  the  reason  of  being  of 
the  conclusion,  so  that  in  the  three  operations  of  the  mind 
nothing  is  intelligible  except  as  it  is  resolved  into  the  notion 
of  being.  It  is  thus  absolutely  clear  that  if  the  adequate 
formal  object  of  the  intellect  were  not  being,  the  intellect 
would  not  have  an  adequate  formal  object  at  all ;  since 
nothing  is  intelligible  except  in  so  far  as  it  is  being  ;  and  all 
those  things  which  are  intelligible  agree  in  this  common 
formal  notion  of  being. 

We  can  also  look  at  this  question  from  a  purely  meta- 
physical point  of  view,  and  observe  that  since  the  root  of 
cognition  is  immateriality,  a  thing  is  intelligible  in  so  far  as 
it  is  immaterial.  Now  it  is  clear  that  the  more  immaterial  a 
thing  is,  the  more  actual  it  is  ;  since  actuality  is  opposed  to 
potentiality,  which  includes  materiality,  so  that  lack  of 
materiality  implies  greater  actuality.  Greater  actuality,  in 
its  turn,  implies  more  perfection,  i.e.  more  positive  being,  and 
it  follows  that  a  thing  is  more  perfect,  more  actual,  more 
immaterial,  more  intelligible,  in  proportion  as  it  is  more 
positively  '  being.' 

The  statement  that  the  adequate  object  of  the  intellect  is 
'  being  as  such  '  is  not,  of  course,  to  be  taken  to  mean  that 
the  intellect  does  not  know  anything  but  '  being  as  such,'  but 
that  it  bears  on  things  precisely  as  they  are  beings  ;  and,  as 
a  consequence,  knows  also  the  differences  and  determinations 
of  being  :  just  as  the  sight  which  bears  on  things  as  they 
are  coloured,  knows  also  the  differences  of  colour.1 

We  have  now  to  ask  what  is  the  proper  formal  object  of  the 
human  intellect ;  that  object,  namely,  which  is  naturally 
known  by  this  particular  kind  of  intellect,  an  intellect  which 
is  found  in  intimate  union  with  a  bodily  organism.  The 
answer  which  S.  Thomas  gives  to  this  question  is  that  this 
object  is  the  natures  of  sensible  things  in  so  far  as  they  are 
universalised,  or  abstracted  from  individuating  conditions. 
By  the  word  '  natures  '  we  understand  all  natures  whether 
substantial  or  accidental ;    but  this  statement  is  not  to  be 

1  Cf.  Summa  Theol.,  1.5,2,0  ;  and  1.79,7,0. 


258         MODERN  THOM1STIC  PHILOSOPHY 

thought  to  mean  that  the  intellect  immediately,  specifically, 
and  perfectly  understands  the  natures  of  material  things  ;  it 
comes  to  the  knowledge  of  them  gradually,  at  first  perceiving 
its  object  under  the  general  forms  of  being,  substance,  etc. 
Nor  do  we  mean  to  assert  that  the  intellect  knows'  nothing 
but  corporeal  things,  but  that  it  perceives  these  natures  first, 
and  because  of  its  own  natural  constitution,  perceiving  other 
things  indirectly,  and  by  means  of  this  proper  object.  This 
idea  is  opposed  to  the  notions  of  all  those  who  grant  man  some 
intuitive  knowledge,  whether  by  way  of  what  are  called 
innate  ideas,  as  did  Plato  and  Descartes,  or  by  an  immediate 
intuition  of  God,  as  did  the  Ontologists.  We  can  approach 
the  question  either  a  posteriori  or  a  priori — using  these 
expressions  in  the  Scholastic  sense — for  we  may  consider 
either  the  way  in  which  the  intellect  understands,  as  we 
experience  it  actually  at  work,  and  so  arrive  at  a  knowledge 
of  its  proper  objects  ;  or  we  may  consider  the  nature  of  the 
intellect  in  itself,  and  deduce  what  must  be  its  object. 

If  we  adopt  the  first  way,  we  see  that  there  are  three  classes 
of  things  which  are  known  by  the  intellect  :  (i)  sensible 
singular  things,  (2)  supersensible  things,  and  (3)  the  natures  of 
sensible  things.  Now  experience  shows  that  purely  super- 
sensible things  cannot  be  the  primary  object  of  the  intellect, 
since  we  always  come  to  know  them  by  way  of  sensible 
things.  The  fact  that  we  cannot  express  our  thoughts  of 
spiritual  entities  except  by  means  of  words  and  phrases 
derived  from  our  knowledge  of  material  ones,  shows  this 
also.  So  the  names,  God,  angel,  spirit,  are  derived  from 
roots  meaning  to  invoke,  send,  and  breathe,  respectively, 
and  this  fact  is  true  in  all  languages.  Nor  can  singular 
things  be  the  primary  object  of  the  human  intellect,  for  we 
always  understand  first  that  a  thing  is  a  being,  and  after- 
wards that  it  is  this  or  that  being ;  for  example,  we  cannot 
understand  the  individual  man  unless  we  have  first  under- 
stood what  human  nature  is.  Hence  it  must  be  the  natures 
of  sensible  things  which  the  intellect  understands  first,  and  of 
its  very  nature.1 

If,  again,  we  consider  the  nature  of  the  intellect  itself,  we 

1  Cf.  Summa  Theol.,  1.84,3,6,7  ;   85,3  ;   87,1-4  ;   88. 


THE   NATURE  OF  THE   INTELLECT         259 

arrive  at  the  same  conclusion,  since  the  object  of  the  intellect 
must  be  proportionate  to  it ;  for,  in  knowing,  it  receives  and 
unites  itself  to  the  known  object,  which  therefore  must  be 
assimilated  or  made  proportionate  to  it.  Now  the  intellect 
is  an  immaterial  form  joined  to  matter,  and  it  follows  that 
the  known  object  must  be  of  the  same  kind,  viz.  the 
dematerialised  nature  of  material  things.1 

The  process  of  cognition  shows  also  that  this  is  so  ;  since, 
when  dealing  with  material  things,  the  intellect  abstracts 
from  individuating  conditions,  and  leaving  them  on  one  side, 
grasps  the  natures  of  the  things,  a  fact  which  would  be 
inexplicable  if  its  objects  were  purely  material,  as  the  Empiri- 
cists maintain.  On  the  other  hand,  while  dealing  with 
immaterial  or  supersensible  things,  though  it  understands 
them,  it  does  so  by  reconverting  them  into  the  sensible,  by 
way  of  the  imagination  ;  which  could  not  be  explained  on 
the  hypothesis  that  its  proper  object  is  the  purely  super- 
sensible, since  in  this  case  we  should  not  understand  spiritual 
things  after  the  manner  of  material  ones,  as  we  do,  but 
material  ones  as  spiritual. 

Intellectual  knowledge,  then,  consists  in  the  reception  by 
the  intellect  of  the  forms  or  essences  abstracted  from 
material  things.  We  see  that  this  is  so,  apart  from  the  con- 
sideration that  the  intellect  is  a  spiritual  faculty  united  to  a 
material  body ;  and  we  can  therefore  use  this  result  to 
strengthen  our  conviction  that  it  is  indeed  spiritual ;  for  it 
is  clear  that  if  intellectual  operations  are  immaterial,  the 
intellect  must  also  be  immaterial.  There  can  be  no  doubt 
that  it  is  impossible  for  an  organic,  or  material,  faculty  to 
know  any  object  without  its  individuating  conditions,  since 
such  a  faculty  depends  in  its  action  on  an  extended  organ,  so 
that  its  action  and  the  result  of  its  action  cannot  be  indepen- 
dent of  extension  ;  i.e.  both  of  them  are  affected  by  a  deter- 
mined quantity.  Thus,  an  organic  faculty  will  only  know 
things  which  have  such  quantity,  or  concrete  beings  with 
their  individuating  conditions.  The  intellect,  on  the  con- 
trary, has  as  its  object,  as  we  have  seen,  natures  abstracted 
from  their  individuating  conditions,  and  it  therefore  cannot 

1  Cf.  Summa  Theol.,  1.12,4  ;   1.55,2  ;    1.84,7. 


260         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

be  an  organic  faculty,  but  must  be  immaterial.  Further,  its 
way  of  grasping  these  unextended  objects  is  itself  unext ended 
or  immaterial ;  since  it  grasps  the  whole  of  its  objects,  and 
all  their  parts,  simultaneously,  in  contradistinction  to  an 
extended  faculty  which  grasps  its  object  partially,  and  the 
parts  separately.  So  the  intellect  sees  the  nature  of  a  thing 
as  a  whole,  whereas  the  sense  sees,  e.g.,  particular  patches  of 
colour. 

Again,  one  of  the  most  striking  characteristics  of  intellectual 
action  is  the  power  of  reflection,  by  which  the  intellect,  as  a 
whole,  considers  itself  as  a  whole,  reflecting  on  its  own  being 
and  nature.  Such  a  process  is  clearly  beyond  the  powers  of 
an  extended  or  material  faculty,  which  cannot  reflect  wholly 
on  itself ;  since,  if  it  has  parts  outside  parts  of  its  very 
nature,  these  parts  cannot  all  be  together  without  destroying 
its  nature.  So  a  piece  of  paper  cannot  be  completely  folded 
on  itself,  so  that  the  whole  of  it  covers  the  whole  of  it ;  but 
only  so  that  one  part  covers  another.1  The  intellect,  then, 
is  immaterial. 

The  cumulative  force  of  all  these  considerations  is  very 
great ;  for  from  whatever  point  of  view  we  regard  the 
intellect  and  its  operations,  we  find  ourselves  led  to  the  con- 
clusion which  we  previously  arrived  at,  from  the  widest 
view  of  its  nature  (when  we  considered  it  as  being  unrestricted 
in  its  range  ;  and  so  being,  in  a  certain  way,  all  things),  viz. 
that  it  is  spiritual  or  immaterial. 

If,  then,  we  grant  that  it  is  so,  it  might  seem  natural  to 
conclude  that  it  is  essentially  active,  since  a  spiritual  thing 
is,  as  such,  not  hampered  by  material  restrictions  ;  and 
should  be  able  to  act  without  being,  as  it  were,  set  in  motion 
by  anything  material.  Nevertheless,  all  that  has  been  said 
so  far  as  to  the  nature  of  intellectual  knowledge  suggests 
that  the  intellect  receives  quite  passively  the  dematerialised 
forms  of  material  things,  having  them  imprinted,  as  it  were, 
upon  it ;  and  not  stretching  out  to  grasp  its  object.  Which 
of  these,  then,  is  the  true  view  of  the  intellect  ?  Is  it  active 
or  passive  ?  This  question  cannot  be  answered  by  a  simple 
affirmation  that  it  is  active  and  a  denial  that  it  is  passive,  or 

1  Cf.  S.  Thomas,  II  Contra  Gentiles,  c.  66 


THE   NATURE  OF  THE   INTELLECT         261 

vice  versa ;  though  such  solutions  have  been  attempted. 
Thus,  the  Transcendentalists,  who  consider  the  principle  of 
immanence — that  we  can  know  only  our  own  thoughts — as 
axiomatic,  deny  the  passivity  of  the  intellect  altogether  ;  as 
do  also  the  Cartesians,  in  consequence  of  their  belief  that  the 
mind  is  always  actually  thinking  ;  and  this  view  is,  generally 
speaking,  held  to  by  all  the  advocates  of  innate  ideas,  who 
think  that  the  intellect  is  complete  in  itself,  through  the 
ideas  which  are  naturally  inborn  in  it.  On  the  other  hand, 
some  Scholastics  speak  as  if  the  intellect  were  wholly  passive, 
and  not  active  at  all,  a  point  of  view  which  is  suggested  by 
the  phrase  '  tabula  rasa,'  the  blank  sheet  of  paper  :  and 
which  may,  without  unfairness,  probably  be  attributed  to 
Locke,  who,  as  Mr.  Morris  says  :  '  rejected  the  view  that  the 
mind  is  active  as  being  evidently  inadmissible.'1 

Though  S.  Thomas  certainly  recognises  a  certain  passivity 
in  the  intellect,  such  passivity  is  not  in  any  way  that  of 
inanimate  things,  such  as  that  of  a  sheet  of  paper,  nor  is  it 
even  of  the  same  kind  as  the  passivity  of  vital  operations  in 
general,  such  as  nutrition,  where  the  nutriment  is  simply 
received  and  absorbed.  For  knowledge  is,  as  we  have 
seen,  an  immanent  action  whereby  the  subject  becomes, 
in  a  certain  way,  the  object,  and  not  vice  versa  ;  and 
is,  moreover,  one  which  enables  it  to  receive  the  object, 
in  accordance  with  its  own  nature,  but  without  changing 
the  object.  If,  then,  the  intellect  is  called  passive,  this  is 
only  in  relation  to  the  object  inasmuch  as  it  is  actuated  by  it, 
not  in  the  sense  that  it  is  itself  devoid  of  activity.  Conse- 
quently, when  S.  Thomas  says  that  the  intellect  is  a  passive 
power,2  he  is  careful  to  explain  that  it  is  only  passive  in 
relation  to  the  object  or  species  which  actuates  it,  because  it 
stands  to  this  in  the  relation  of  potency  to  act.  It  is  there- 
fore perfected  by  the  reception  of  the  species,  and  becomes 
actively  understanding.  So  if  we  consider  the  intellect  in 
relation  to  the  act  of  understanding  we  shall  say  that  it  is 
active,  since  it  produces  this  act.    What  was  said  as  to  the 

1  Cf.  C.  R.  Morris,  Locke,  Berkeley,  Hume,  p.  26.     (Clarendon  Press, 

I93i) 

a  Cf.  Summa  Theol.,  1.79,2. 


262         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

activity  of  cognition  in  general,1  finds  its  application  here  ; 
since,  though  the  intellect  in  no  sense  makes  the  reality,  but 
has  to  be  actuated  by  it  (here  is  its  passivity),  yet,  at  the 
same  time,  it  actively  apprehends  it,  and  by  its  own  action 
is  simultaneously  conscious  of  itself.  So  '  the  intellect  in 
act  and  the  thing  understood  in  act  are  one  and  the  same,' 
being  unified  in  the  identity  of  one  and  the  same  act. 

The  intellect  which  actually  understands,  in  this  way,  is 
called  by  the  Scholastics  the  passive  intellect,  or  the 
intellectus  possibilis  (since  it  can  become  all  things)  ;  in 
conformity  with  their  general  rule  as  to  the  way  in  which 
the  faculties  should  be  discriminated,  viz.  with  reference  to 
their  objects  ;  and  this  intellect  is,  as  we  have  seen,  in 
potency  with  respect  to  the  objects  which  actuate  it. 

That  such  passivity  as  this  must  be  ascribed  to  the  intellect, 
if  we  wish  to  maintain  that  it  is  a  faculty  which  discovers, 
and  does  not  create,  its  object,  is  undeniable,  when  we  con- 
sider that  since  the  intellect  in  act  and  the  intelligible  in  act 
are  one,  an  intellect  which  was  not  potential  to  its  objects 
would  be  those  objects  actually,  and  so  actually  universal 
being ;  since  the  object  of  the  intellect  is,  as  we  have  seen, 
universal  being.  Intelligence  of  this  kind  is  evidently  not  to 
be  found  among  finite  beings  which  come  to  know  a  limited 
number  of  objects  gradually,  and  so  are  potential  or  passive 
with  respect  to  them.  To  deny  this  would  be  to  identify  the 
human  intellect  with  the  divine,  making  it  the  intelligible 
forms  of  all  things  simultaneously  and  actually,  knowing 
itself,  and  so  all  things,  perfectly  and  at  once  ;  a  claim  so 
incredibly  arrogant  as  to  be  intolerable,  apart  from  its 
obvious  falsity  in  the  light  of  experience. 

A  corollary  as  to  our  knowledge  of  singular  things  follows 
from  the  Thomistic  teaching  on  the  proper  object  of  the 
human  intellect ;  for  if  this  object  be  the  natures  of  material 
things,  which  are  universal,  it  is  clear  that  the  intellect  is  not 
primarily  and  essentially  directed  to  the  material  things'  as 
singular,  but  only  as  universal.  If,  then,  we  know  singular 
things  at  all,  as  we  certainly  do,  since  we  judge  and  reason 
about  them,  and  distinguish  them  from  the  universal,  such 

1  Cf.  pp.  216  f. 


THE   NATURE  OF  THE  INTELLECT        263 

knowledge  can  only  be  indirect  and  secondary,  and  obtained 
by  comparing  their  universal  nature  with  the  concrete  image 
which  we  have  of  them  as  pictured  in  the  imagination. 
Moreover,  since  the  source  of  singularity  or  individuality  is 
matter,  and  matter  is  not  intelligible  in  itself,  for  the  root 
of  knowledge  is  immateriality,  it  is  impossible  to  maintain 
that  the  individual  qua  individual  is  intelligible  in  itself,  and 
directly.  It  can  only  become  so  in  so  far  as  the  universal 
form  is  seen  to  belong  to  this  particular  concrete  imaged 
object.  Suarez,  in  holding  the  contradictory  view,  that  the 
intellect  knows  singular  things  directly,  recognises  that  it  is 
opposed  to  that  of  S.  Thomas  and  all  the  Thomists  ;  but 
seems  to  have  been  led  to  adopt  it  for  fear  of  falling  into  the 
opinion  held  by  Cajetan  that  we  know  singulars  confusedly 
only,  and  not  distinctly,  i.e.  as  distinct  one  from  another. 
This  consequence,  however,  in  no  way  follows  from  the 
Thomistic  position,  and  is  indeed  excluded  by  it ;  and  if 
the  view  of  Cajetan  is  an  exaggeration  in  the  direction  of 
intellectualism,  that  of  Suarez  undoubtedly  tends  to  confuse 
sensible  and  intellectual  knowledge  ;  which  is,  at  least,  an 
equally  dangerous  deviation  in  the  direction  of  empiricism. 

We  have  now  a  general  notion  of  the  nature  of  the  intellect 
which  we  have  seen  to  be  an  immaterial  power  by  which 
man  knows  abstract  universal  natures  primarily,  and  singu- 
lar things  secondarily  ;  in  order  to  do  which  his  intellect 
has  to  be  acted  on  by  the  objects,  and  so  is  said  to  be  passive, 
though  considered  from  other  points  of  view  it  is  active. 

From  this  general  view  of  its  nature  it  is  natural  to  pass 
to  an  enquiry  into  its  way  of  working. 


CHAPTER  XII 

THE   ORIGIN   OF  IDEAS 

The  Empiricists — Innate  Ideas — The  Transcendentalists  and  Hegel 
— The  Difficulty  of  the  Question — The  Thomist  Solution — The 
Active  Intellect — Its  Necessity  and  Function — Summary  of  the 
Intellectual  Process. 

The  question  '  how  do  we  know  ?  '  naturally  follows  the  dis- 
cussion of  the  question  '  what  do  we  know  ?  ' ;  and  is 
generally  called  by  modern  writers  the  problem  of  the 
origin  of  ideas. 

As  our  purpose  is  to  explain  the  Thomistic  view  of  mental 
action,  it  will  be  unnecessary  to  subject  to  detailed  criticism 
the  many  divergent  opinions  which,  particularly  in  recent 
times,  have  been  put  forward  on  this  subject.  At  the  same 
time  it  is  useful  to  enumerate  them  shortly,  since  they  throw 
light  on  the  real  nature  and  difficulty  of  this  question.  These 
views,  generally  speaking,  are  based  on  conclusions  pre- 
viously reached  by  their  exponents  on  the  relation  between 
body  and  mind,  and  the  nature  of  their  union.  Thus,  those 
who  deny  the  immateriality  of  the  mind,  making  it  something 
bodily,  will  necessarily  say  that  ideas  arise  entirely  from  the 
senses  and  sensible  things,  while  those  who,  at  the  opposite 
extreme,  regard  the  mind  as  wholly  spiritual,  and  an  acci- 
dental adjunct  only  of  the  body,  naturally  conclude  that 
ideas  originate  independently  of  material  objects  and  the 
senses  ;  while  finally,  if  it  be  maintained  that  both  mind 
and  body  are  essential  elements  of  human  nature,  the  origin 
of  ideas  will  be  attributed  to  the  senses  and  intellect  in 
conjunction. 

Thus  we  find  three  general  classes  of  opinion  : 
i.  That  of  the  Empiricists,  according  to  whom  sensible 
experience  is  the  adequate  cause,  not  merely  of  sensible 

264 


THE  ORIGIN   OF   IDEAS  265 

knowledge,  but  also  of  intellectual.  The  movement  which 
eventually  resulted  in  the  distinct  formulation  of  this  view 
was  begun  by  John  Locke,  who  recognised  two  processes  in 
the  acquisition  of  ideas, — sensation  and  reflection.  He  thus 
maintained,  in  a  fashion,  the  distinction  between  the  senses 
and  the  intellect.  But  it  is  to  be  observed,  that  since  he 
accorded  to  sensation  the  acquisition  of  simple  ideas  which 
represent  the  primary  qualities  of  bodies,  such  as  solidity, 
extension,  etc.,  which  ideas,  according  to  him,  really  resemble 
these  qualities,  while  by  reflection  we  only  come  to  know 
the  internal  operations  of  our  own  minds  ;  and,  further, 
that  by  putting  together  the  simple  ideas,  already  acquired 
by  sensation,  we  form  compound  ones,  he,  in  fact,  equiv- 
alently  asserts  that  reflection  adds  nothing  new  to  the 
fabric  of  science,  and  the  whole  weight  of  the  production  of 
ideas  rests  on  sensation.  It  does  not  seem  as  if  Locke 
realised  all  the  implications  of  his  own  doctrine,  but  they 
were  quickly  brought  out  by  Condillac,  in  France  ;  and  by 
Hume,  the  two  Mills,  and  Bain,  in  our  own  country.  These 
all  got  rid  of  the  power  of  reflection  as  being  useless,  and 
substituted  for  it  the  alleged  laws  of  the  association  of  ideas, 
so  that  all  ideas  are  but  transformed  sensations.  From  this 
theory  their  doctrine  came  to  be  known  as  Associationism.1 
2.  The  second  class  of  opinion  maintains  that  ideas  essen- 
tially originate  independently  of  sensation.  This  view  is 
found,  in  an  undiluted  form,  in  the  doctrine  of  innate  ideas 
professed  by  Plato,  Descartes,  Rosmini,  and  others.  Plato 
emphasised  the  distinction  between  opinion  and  science,  of 
which  the  first  only  is  derivable  from  sense  experience. 
Science,  then,  must  come  to  the  mind  independently  of  such 
experience,  so  that  the  ideas  which  constitute  it  will  be  native 
to  the  intellect,  which  is  supposed  to  have  known  them  in  a 
previous  existence.  Knowledge,  therefore,  in  this  view, 
would  be  reminiscence  ;  though  perhaps  this  phrase  is  not 
to  be  taken  too  literally.  According  to  Descartes,  it  is 
essential  to  the  soul  to  think.  Now  thought  is  impossible 
without  ideas,  so  that  the  soul  must  from  the  beginning 

1  For  a  short  account  of  the  details  of  this  theory  cf.  e.g.  McDougall, 
Outline  of  Psychology,  pp.  237  ff.    Stout,  Manual  of  Psychology,  pp.  117  ff. 


266         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

possess  at  least  some  congenital  or  innate  ideas,  though  Des- 
cartes did  not  deny  altogether  the  possibility  of  acquiring 
ideas.  Such  acquired  ideas  fall,  in  his  view,  into  two  classes  ; 
viz.  :  (a)  those  which  are,  properly  speaking,  acquired  by 
way  of  the  senses  and  which  he  calls  '  adventitious  '  ;  and 
(b)  those  which  are  evolved  by  the  mind  itself,  through  the 
association  of  sensible  images,  which  he  calls  '  fictitious  ' 
ideas.  Rosmini,  lastly,  held  that  the  idea  of  being  in  general 
is  innate,  for  he  considered  that  it  is  impossible  to  think  until 
this  idea  is  present. 

This  general  class  of  opinion  is  also  represented,  in  a  modi- 
fied form,  by  the  Transcendental  Idealists,  who  consider 
that  intelligible  objects  altogether  transcend  sense  experi- 
ence, so  that  the  origin  of  our  intellectual  ideas  must  be 
sought  in  an  analysis  of  thought  alone.  It  is  put  forward  in 
various  forms  by  Kant,  Fichte,  Schelling,  and  Hegel.  In  his 
first  period,  Kant  accepted  the  theory  of  innate  ideas  derived 
from  Leibniz  and  Wolff ;  but  later,  under  the  pressure  of 
Empiricist  and  Sceptical  objections,  abandoned  it,  and  felt 
obliged  to  recognise  that  there  is,  in  our  thinking,  a  universal 
and  necessary  element,  as  well  as  the  fact  that  it  is,  at  least 
partially,  derived  from  the  external  world.  The  necessary 
element,  which  is  formal,  comes  from  our  own  minds  ;  the 
material  element,  from  without.  The  formal  elements  he 
calls  '  categories,'  of  which  the  intellect  possesses  twelve, 
into  which  all  the  objects  of  our  knowledge  are  fitted.  From 
this  it  appears  that  we  do  not  know  external  things  as  they 
are  in  themselves,  but  as  they  are  moulded  by  these  forms  or 
categories  ;  and  there  is,  therefore,  no  guarantee  that  our 
intellectual  knowledge  will  correspond  with  external  reality. 
Fichte  and  Schelling  carried  the  ideas  of  Kant  to  their  logical 
conclusion,  by  abolishing  the  '  thing-in-itself,'  and  with  it 
the  individual ;  leaving  nothing  but  mind-in-general,  or  the 
Absolute.  The  development  of  this  line  of  thought  is  com- 
pleted by  Hegel,  who  taught  that  the  absolute  and  universal 
principle  of  cognition  is  the  Idea  of  Being  in  its  most  abstract 
form,  that  is,  '  Pure  Thought.'  In  the  first  moment  the  Idea 
of  Pure  Being  is  pure  indetermination,  for  determination 
implies  an  opposite,  and  in  the  beginning  there  can  be  no 


THE  ORIGIN  OF  IDEAS  267 

opposite.  Now  pure  indetermination  is  pure  not-being,  and 
therefore  Pure-Being  is  Pure  Not-Being  ;  so  that  the  Idea 
and  Reality  of  Being  is  itself  its  contradictory,  and  the 
reconciliation  of  contradictories.  Thus  the  Idea  of  Being 
contains  that  of  Not-Being,  which  is  therefore  deduced  from 
it.  Moreover,  Being  which  is  not-Being,  and  not-Being 
which  is  Being  is  Becoming,  which  is  neither  Being  nor  not- 
Being.  So  that  the  third  Idea  of  Becoming  is  deduced  from 
the  first  two.  This  process  can  be  continued  indefinitely  till 
all  the  Ideas  are  deduced,  and  it  is  this  which  Hegel  attempts 
to  do  in  his  Logic.  The  origin  of  our  ideas,  then,  in  his  view, 
is  to  be  found  in  this  first  Idea  of  Pure  Being  ;  and  our  whole 
knowledge  is  merely  the  development  of  this  Idea,  by  means 
of  the  Dialectic  method. 

We  may  notice,  in  passing,  that  when  it  is  said  :  '  in  the 
beginning  there  can  be  no  opposite,'  this  is  equivalent  to 
saying  :  '  in  the  beginning  nothing  can  be  an  opposite,'  and, 
in  this  case,  there  is  an  opposite  of  Being,  viz.  nothing. 
Being  therefore  can  be  determined,  not  it  is  true  by  anything 
external,  nor  yet  as  a  genus  or  species,  since  it  is  transcendent, 
but  in  its  positive  entity  as  opposed  to  Not-Being,  and  conse- 
quently none  of  the  conclusions  follow.  They  can  only  hold 
good  if  the  phrase  '  pure  indetermination  '  be  taken  equivo- 
cally, signifying  the  entire  lack  of  determination  of  Being  to 
genus  and  species,  in  the  first  place  ;  and  an  absolute  void 
without  determination  of  any  sort,  in  the  second.1 

The  foregoing  theories  bring  out  clearly  the  difficulty  of 
this  question  of  the  origin  of  ideas,  for,  on  the  one  hand, 
those  who  hold  that  all  knowledge  is  sense  knowledge  can 
urge  that  if  this  be  not  true  it  is  impossible  to  explain  the 
fact  that  all  our  actions,  even  the  most  abstract,  are  only 
intelligible  in  terms  of  sense  and  sensible  images  ;  while,  on 
the  other  hand,  those  who  think  that  ideas  originate  indepen- 
dently of  sensation  have  strong  grounds  for  asserting 
that  the  opposing  theory  cannot  be  true,  inasmuch  as  the 
objects  of  the  intellect,  which  are  universal  and  necessary, 

1  For  a  full  explanation  of  Hegel's  theory  vide  Stace,  The  Philosophy 
of  Hegel,  esp.  pp.  90  ff.  ;  and,  for  its  criticism,  Garigou-Lagrange,  De 
Revelatione,  Vol.  I,  pp.  244-272,  esp.  p.  271. 


268         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

and  the  objects  of  sense,  which  are  singular  and  contingent, 
are  of  different  kinds,  so  that  one  cannot  be  derived  from  the 
other.  Thus  we  seem  to  be  on  the  horns  of  a  dilemma  :  unless 
we  accept  Empiricism  we  cannot  explain  the  facts  of  experi- 
ence ;  and  if  we  do  accept  it,  we  cannot  account  for  the 
necessary  and  universal  character  of  our  ideas. 

3.  The  theory  of  S.  Thomas  resolves  this  apparent  contra- 
diction by  combining  both  the  elements  of  the  situation 
in  a  higher  synthesis,  and  is  indicated  by  the  phrase  :  '  Know- 
ledge begins  in  the  senses  and  is  perfected  in  the  intellect.' 
According  to  this  view  we  are  not  in  possession  of  ready-made 
ideas  ;  nor  are  they  infused  into  us  by  God,  or  any  separated 
Form  ;  nor  do  we  gain  them  by  intuition  of  God  and  the 
Divine  Ideas  ;  while,  on  the  other  hand,  the  senses  are  not 
the  proper  cause  of  the  ideas  of  the  intellect ;  and  the  mind 
therefore  has  to  acquire  them.  As  we  saw,  it  is  at  first 
potential  to  knowledge,  not  actually  knowing,  and  so  is 
passive  ;  but,  in  order  that  it  may  be  in  possession  of  its 
ideas,  it  needs  to  be  actuated  and  determined.  Are  we,  then, 
to  say  that  it  actuates  and  determines  itself,  or  that  it  is 
actuated  by  something  other  than  itself  ?  Both  suppositions 
seem  impossible,  for  a  thing  cannot  actuate  itself,  since  to  do 
so  it  would  already  have  to  possess  that  perfection  which  it  is 
supposed  to  bestow  on  itself,  nothing  being  able  to  give  what 
it  does  not  possess  :  nor  yet  can  it  be  actuated  by  something 
other  than  itself,  for  the  only  thing  other  than  the  intellect 
which  is  present  in  this  situation  is  the  material  objects  of 
the  senses  which,  being  material,  are  not  proportionate  to 
the  immaterial  intellect,  and  so  cannot  perfect  or  actuate  it. 
In  this  impasse,  if  we  re-examine  the  statement  just  made,  we 
see  that  though  there  can  be  no  possible  doubt  that  the 
intellect  cannot  actuate  itself,  since  the  hypothesis  that  it 
did  so  would  involve  a  contradiction,  yet  the  same  is  not 
true  of  the  assertion  that  the  only  elements  in  the  situation 
are  the  intellect  and  the  material  objects,  for  no  contradiction 
is  involved  in  the  supposition  that  there  is  some  active  agent 
which  concurs  in  the  process  of  understanding,  by  demateri- 
alising  the  objects  of  sense,  and  so  bringing  them  to  a  state 
in  which  they  are  fit  to  be  perfections,  or  actuations,  of  the 


THE  ORIGIN  OF  IDEAS  269 

immaterial  intellect.  We  are,  therefore,  driven  by  the  logic 
of  the  facts  to  assert  the  existence  of  such  an  active  agent, 
as  the  only  means  of  extricating  ourselves  from  an  impossible 
situation.  What  is  the  nature  of  this  agent  ?  Absolutely 
speaking,  it  might  be  something  extrinsic  both  to  us  and  the 
material  objects.  The  whole  of  our  experience  of  the  process 
of  knowledge,  as  well  as  the  requirement  that  we  should  be 
sure  of  its  truth,  renders,  however,  such  a  supposition 
untenable.  For  the  whole  intellectual  process  exhibits  itself 
as  a  gradual  one,  by  which  we  come  into  possession  of  know- 
ledge of  things,  slowly  and  with  much  effort,  passing  pro- 
gressively from  confused  notions  to  distinct  ones,  and  from 
the  widest  ideas,  such  as  that  of  being,  to  specific  ones,  such 
as  that  of  man.  It  is  easy  to  see,  that  if  ideas  were  implanted 
in  our  minds  by  some  agent  outside  ourselves,  this  laborious 
process  becomes  inexplicable,  for  we  should  pass  in  a  flash 
from  nescience  to  full  knowledge,  as  soon  as  the  ideas  were 
imparted  to  us.  Moreover,  if  the  ideas  are  given  to  us  in 
this  extrinsic  fashion,  how  could  we  know  that  they  corres- 
pond to  the  reality  ?  Evidently,  this  would  only  be  possible 
if  we  knew  what  the  reality  was,  independently  of  them,  in 
which  case  they  become  quite  useless.  If,  on  the  other  hand, 
we  do  not  know  their  correspondence  with  reality  we  cannot 
have  any  assurance  of  their  truth,  and  so  are  left  a  prey  to 
Scepticism. 

If,  then,  we  dismiss  the  hypothesis  of  an  external  agent 
which  implants  the  ideas  in  us,  and  further  observe,  what  is 
also  clear,  that  the  material  objects  themselves  cannot  be 
the  formative  cause  of  our  ideas,  for  the  very  reason  that 
they  are  material,  the  only  conceivable  cause  of  them  will  be 
some  agent  within  us.  In  other  words,  the  mind  of  man 
must  possess  some  active  power  by  which  he  is  enabled  to 
dematerialise  the  objects,  and  make  them  fit  objects  of  the 
intellect.  It  is  precisely  the  existence  of  such  a  power  which 
S.  Thomas  asserts,  since  v/ithout  it  we  can  give  no  satisfac- 
tory account  of  the  origin  of  our  ideas.  As  it  must  evidently 
be  an  intellectual  power  he  calls  it  the  '  active  intellect '  or 
'  intellectus  agens.'1 

1  For  a  summary  of  this  argument  cf.  Cajetan  Comm.  in  1.79,3. 


270         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

The  function,  then,  of  this  mental  power  is  to  demateri- 
alise  the  objects,  as  offered  by  the  imagination,  in  such  a 
way  as  to  make  them  able  to  be  dealt  with  by  the  intellect 
which  is  to  understand  them.  It  will,  therefore,  abstract  the 
formal  element  in  them,  leaving  aside  the  material  elements, 
and  seize  the  universal,  neglecting  those  characters  which 
make  the  objects  individuals.  These  objects  are  those 
offered  by  the  imagination,  as  we  have  just  said,  so  that  the 
imagination  has  a  necessary  part  to  play  in  the  intellectual 
process,  by  offering  the  material  on  which  the  mind  is  to 
work.  This  necessary  condition  of  human  knowledge — 
necessary,  because  man  is  partly  material,  partly  spiritual — 
has  very  obvious  dangers,  since  it  is  quite  easy  for  us  to 
mistake  the  imagined  picture  of  a  thing  for  its  real  nature. 
Such  an  error  will  always  be  made  when  the  conclusions  of 
one  science  are  imported  bodily,  and  as  they  stand,  into 
another,  as,  for  example,  if  a  man  were  to  argue  from  the 
determinism  which  physical  science  recognises  in  nature  to 
the  impossibility  of  freedom  in  human  life.  The  image, 
then,  presented  to  the  intellect  needs  to  be  changed  and 
made  abstract,  or  as  S.  Thomas  often  says,  '  illuminated  '  ; 
the  active  intellect  being  a  sort  of  mental  X-ray  which 
pierces  through  the  flesh  or  matter  of  the  image  to  reveal  its 
internal  nature.  But  just  as  such  rays  do  not  perceive  the 
internal  structure  themselves,  but  only  reveal  it,  so  the  active 
intellect  does  not  itself  know  the  universal  form  or  nature 
which  it  reveals  in  the  image,  this  being  the  function  of  the 
passive  intellect,  of  which  we  have  already  spoken  at  length. 

To  complete  this  account  of  the  way  in  which  ideas  originate 
we  must  recall  what  was  said  earlier.1  Since,  in  intellectual 
knowledge,  the  object  itself  is  not  cognitively  present  to  the 
mind,  the  intellect  has  to  form  for  itself  a  representation  of 
it  to  be  the  term  of  cognition,  i.e.  it  forms  an  expressed 
species  of  the  object,  a  formal  concept,  or  '  mental  word  '  or 
expression  of  what  it  has  already  understood  by  means  of 
the  impressed  species.  This  concept,  then,  is  not  the  thing 
which  is  understood  ;  what  we  know  is  not  our  own  ideas,  but 
the  object,  in  and  along  with  these  ideas. 

1  Cf.  Part  II,  Ch.  viii. 


THE  ORIGIN  OF  IDEAS  271 

So  the  whole  process  of  intellectual  cognition  may  be  sum- 
marised as  follows  :  though  it  is  not  to  be  supposed  that 
the  elements  which  we  find,  by  analysis,  in  the  act  have  a 
temporal  sequence,  or  work  on  one  another  like  the  wheels 
of  a  watch.  The  intelligible  object  is  in  the  intellect  in  a  two- 
fold fashion,  first,  as  impressed  and  the  principle  of  know- 
ledge, secondly,  as  expressed  and  its  term.  Now  the  im- 
pressed object  is  an  habitual  representation,  which  is  called 
the  intelligible  species,  and  is  abstracted  from  the  images  in 
the  imagination  by  the  active  intellect  whose  instruments 
these  images  are.1  This  impressed  form  of  the  object  is  the 
principle  which  determines  the  passive  intellect  and  co- 
operates with  it  efficiently  in  the  act  of  understanding,  and 
so  makes  the  intellect,  when  acting,  one  with  the  object. 
Lastly,  the  expressed  species  is  the  actual  representation  of 
this  object,  in  which  the  passive  intellect,  now  in  act,  as  it 
were,  says,  or  expresses,  the  object  to  itself,  and  actually 
assimilates  it  to  itself.  This  mental  word  or  concept  is  not 
the  act  of  understanding  itself,  but  the  intrinsic  term  of  this 
act,  giving  satisfaction  and  completion  to  it,  just  as  in  the 
process  of  generation  or  reproduction  satisfaction  and  com- 
pletion is  found  in  the  conception  and  birth  of  offspring. 

1  John  of  S.  Thomas,  Phil.  Nat.,  P.  Ill,  Q.  10,  A.  2. 


CHAPTER  XIII 

THE  INTELLECTUAL  APPETITE  \    THE  WILL 

Its  Existence — Nature — What  Necessity  is — Freedom  of  the  Will — 
History  of  the  Problem — Summary  of  Opinions — Arguments  in 
Favour  of  Liberty — The  Limits  of  Liberty — Views  on  the  Nature 
of  Liberty — The  Answer  to  Indeterminism — The  Answer  to 
Psychological  Determinism — Summary  of  results  arrived  at. 

In  the  preceding  chapters  we  have  dealt  with  the  nature  and 
work  of  the  mind  in  knowing.  Another  aspect  of  intellectual 
life  must  now  be  investigated  in  order  to  complete  our  view 
of  its  activities,  viz.  its  volitional  aspect,  for  it  is  universally 
recognised  that  it  exhibits  itself  not  only  in  cognition,  but 
also  in  conation.  No  doubt  is  possible  with  respect  to  the 
fact  that  some  conative  activity,  or  striving  in  general,  is  to 
be  found  in  man,  for  experience  speaks  too  plainly.  Moreover, 
we  have  already  noticed  that  action  must  be  in  some  deter- 
minate direction,  or  towards  some  end,  otherwise  it  would 
have  no  direction,  and  so  would  not  exist.  It  follows,  then, 
that  to  every  species  of  activity  will  be  attached  a  certain 
striving  to  attain  the  end  to  which  it  is  directed,  though  in 
the  case  of  inanimate  agents,  or  those  without  knowledge  or 
consciousness,  we  cannot  call  such  striving  '  willing,'  in  any 
proper  sense.  In  things  which  know  the  end  to  which  their 
actions  are  directed  we  shall  first  begin  to  have  desire  for  it, 
for  in  their  knowing  of  it,  they  will  perceive  it  as  something 
which  is  either  suitable,  or  unsuitable,  to  them.  Desire,  or 
appetite,  will  therefore  accompany,  or  rather  follow,  all 
kinds  of  cognitive  action,  whether  sensible  or  intellectual ; 
so  that  if  we  grant  the  existence  of  an  intellectual  power  in 
man  we  shall  be  unable  to  deny  him  an  intellectual  appetite, 
or  will,  also.  As  was  pointed  out,  in  dealing  with  the 
faculties  in  general,  such  a  power  is  not  to  be  supposed  to  be 
a  thing  in  its  own  right,  but  is  merely  the  means  which  a  man 

272 


THE  INTELLECTUAL  APPETITE  273 

uses  in  striving  to  attain  a  desired  end,  just  as  the  intellect 
is  the  means  he  uses  to  unite  the  object  to  himself  in  cogni- 
tion. Hence  it  is  not  the  intellect  which  knows,  properly 
speaking,  but  the  man ,  by  its  means  ;  and  not  the  will  which 
desires,  but  man,  by  means  of  it. 

The  Nature  of  the  Will. 

What,  then,  is  the  nature  of  this  intellectual  appetite  ? 
Clearly  it  is  distinguished  from  the  blind  direction  to  parti- 
cular ends  which  characterises  the  actions  of  inanimate 
things,  and  also  that  conscious  desire  of  sensible  objects 
which  is  to  be  observed  in  the  actions  of  animals,  since  it 
follows  neither  on  the  intrinsic  tendency  of  man's  nature  as 
a  material  being,  nor  on  knowledge  which  is  purely  sensible  ; 
though  it  is  true  that  he  has  tendencies  which  follow  on  both 
of  these.  We  observe  that  such  tendencies  in  beings  other 
than  man  are  characterised  by  necessity ;  for  a  stone 
necessarily  falls  to  the  ground,  and  a  hungry  animal  neces- 
sarily desires  suitable  food.  This  suggests  that  the  same 
may  be  the  case  with  the  will.  Even  though  it  follows  on 
intellectual  knowledge,  not  on  sense  perception,  it  may 
necessarily  desire  what  it  thus  knows. 

Before  discussing  the  thorny  question  whether  the  will  is 
necessitated,  it  will  be  useful  to  notice  some  points  both 
about  the  will,  and  about  necessity,  in  order  to  have  a 
clearer  idea  of  each  of  them. 

In  the  first  place,  the  will,  being  the  appetite  which  follows 
the  intellect,  will  have  as  its  objects  those  things  which  are 
the  objects  of  the  intellect ;  now,  however,  regarded  as 
things  which  are  desirable,  or  good,  and  not  merely  know- 
able.  Since  the  object  of  the  intellect  is  being  as  such,  that 
of  the  will  will  be  being  in  general,  regarded  as  desirable,  or 
suitable,  and  this  we  call  the  good  in  general.  Similarly,  the 
object  proportionate  and  proper  to  the  human  will  is  the 
good  in  material  things,  just  as  the  human  intellect  is  directed 
to  the  being  of  material  things. 

With  regard  to  the  acts  of  the  will  there  is  clearly  a  dis- 
tinction between  those  which  proceed  immediately  from  the 
will  itself,  such  as  a  particular  desire  or  wish,  as  was  that 


274         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

of  Browning  when  he  says  :  '  Oh,  to  be  in  England,  now  that 
April's  there  '  ;  and  those  which  proceed  from  some  other 
faculty,  though  under  the  influence  and  direction  of  the  will, 
as  are,  for  example,  acts  of  walking  and  speaking.  The 
first  class  are  called  elicited,  and  the  second  sanctioned  acts. 

Necessity. 

Secondly,  with  regard  to  necessity,  we  notice  that  it  may 
arise  either  from  an  intrinsic,  or  an  extrinsic,  cause  ;  and  an 
intrinsic  cause,  being  the  nature  of  the  thing,  such  necessity 
is  called  natural  necessity  ;  whereby  a  thing  is  obliged  to  act, 
if  it  acts  at  all,  in  accordance  with  its  nature.  There  are  two 
extrinsic  causes  from  either  of  which  necessity  may  arise, 
viz.  efficient  and  final  causes.  If  some  external  agent  forces 
a  thing  to  act  in  a  certain  way,  such  necessity  is  called  com- 
pelling necessity  ;  while  if  the  thing  is  obliged  to  act  in  a 
particular  way  in  order  to  attain  a  given  end,  we  have  what 
is  known  as  hypothetical  necessity,  since  it  must  so  act  on 
the  hypothesis  that  it  wishes  to  gain  this  end. 

If  we  now  apply  these  notions  to  the  will,  we  see  that 
though  the  will  can  be  bound  both  by  natural  and  hypo- 
thetical necessity,  it  cannot  be  under  the  dominion  of  com- 
pelling necessity.  The  reason  for  the  last  part  of  this  state- 
ment is,  that  since  compelling  necessity,  by  definition,  acts 
on  the  will  from  without,  it  cannot  affect  the  initiation,  but 
only  the  execution  of  an  act  of  the  will,  since  the  former  pro- 
ceeds from  within.  Such  necessity,  then,  does  not  affect  the 
act  at  its  source,  but  at  most  prevents  the  will  from  setting 
in  motion  the  faculty  on  which  force  is  exerted.  Thus  com- 
pulsion may  prevent  a  man  from  walking,  but  not  from  willing 
to  walk  ;  so  that  external  force,  or  '  violence,'  as  S.  Thomas 
calls  it,  cannot  dominate  the  will's  elicited  acts,  but  only  its 
sanctioned  ones.  But  if  such  compulsion  as  this  is  impossible, 
the  will  is,  nevertheless,  necessitated  from  within,  because 
whenever  it  is  desirous  of  some  object,  it  cannot  help  also 
desiring  the  means  which  are  necessary  for  its  attainment  ; 
as  a  man  who  wishes  to  be  in  some  place,  at  a  distance,  must 
also  wish  to  be  transported  over  the  distance,  and  so  desire 
some  means  of  transport.     In  this  way  the  will  is  hypo- 


THE  INTELLECTUAL  APPETITE  275 

thetically  necessitated.  But  it  is  also  naturally  necessitated, 
for  it  has  its  own  definite  nature,  and  must,  therefore,  of 
necessity,  tend  towards  that  nature's  end,  and  obey  that 
nature's  laws.  The  end  to  which  the  will  is  thus  naturally, 
and  so  necessarily,  directed  is  good  in  general,  so  that  it  is 
bound  to  wish  for  complete  goodness,  or  that  which  is 
suitable  to  man  in  every  respect,  perfecting  him  in  every  way 
and  so  giving  him  complete  happiness.  To  suppose  it  could 
will  otherwise  than  this  is  evidently  an  hypothesis  which  is 
contradictory  in  itself,  since  then  it  would  will  something 
which  does  not  suit  it,  and  so,  is  not  desirable,  and  cannot 
be  willed. 

The  will  as  nature  is,  no  doubt,  influenced  by  the  life- 
history  of  the  human  race,  and  by  inherited  tendencies  ; 
though  it  should  be  noticed  that  such  tendencies  cannot 
alter  the  very  nature,  or  essence,  of  the  will  in  itself,  since 
to  do  this  would  be  to  destroy  it  altogether  ;  but  can  only 
modify  its  actions.  Moreover,  they  cannot  modify  it  to  the 
extent  of  never  allowing  it  to  act  in  accordance  with  its 
nature,  since  this,  again,  would  be  equivalent  to  destroying 
that  nature. 

Though  the  will  be  necessitated  in  the  ways  we  have 
mentioned,  yet  such  necessity  cannot  reach  to  determining 
it  to  exercise  the  act  of  willing  either  what  is  entirely  good 
for  the  whole  man,  or  thosemeans  which  are  necessarily  con- 
nected with  some  willed  end  ;  since  the  intellect  may  not 
put  these  before  the  will ;  in  which  case  it  will  not  exercise 
the  act  of  desiring  them.  If,  however,  they  are  put  before  it, 
it  must  desire  them  of  necessity. 

Freedom  of  the  Will. 

We  see,  then,  that  our  wills  are  necessitated,  at  least  to 
some  extent  ;  and  this  leads  us  to  ask  whether  such  necessi- 
tation  extends  to  all  our  volitions,  a  question  which  has 
given  rise  to  interminable  disputes.  Dr.  Johnson  cut  short 
this  discussion  in  characteristic  fashion,  by  saying  :  '  All 
theory  is  against  freedom  of  the  will,  all  experience  for  it.' 

Whether  this  summary  of  the  state  of  the  case  is  true  we 
shall  soon  see,  but  it  is  not  difficult  to  understand  why  this 


276         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

question  has  so  continually  engaged  the  attention  of  philo- 
sophers, for  it  is  one  which  has  a  very  definite  bearing  on  our 
everyday  life  ;  and,  in  particular,  it  seems  very  difficult,  if 
not  impossible,  to  attach  any  meaning  to  the  word '  morality,' 
if  human  liberty  be  denied.  How  can  a  man  be  said  to  act 
rightly  or  wrongly,  to  do  good  or  evil,  if  he  is  incapable  of 
acting  in  any  other  way,  or  of  refraining  from  action  ?  Can 
we  say  that  a  machine  which  works  accurately  is  virtuous,  or 
one  which  does  not,  vicious,  and  so  worthy  of  punishment  or 
reward  ?  So,  it  has  always  been  felt,  that  unless  liberty  can 
be  defended,  morality  and  the  essential  dignity  of  man  would 
be  destroyed. 

These  may,  perhaps,  be  thought  to  be  but  sentimental 
considerations  ;  and  we  ought,  then,  to  view  the  subject 
impartially"  in  itself,  and  not  merely  in  the  consequences 
which  a  denial  of  freedom  would  entail. 

Whether  freewill  exist  or  not,  there  can  be  little  doubt 
that  we  conceive  of  it  as  a  '  power  of  choice  '  ;x  and  since  no 
choice  is  possible  with  regard  to  that  which  presents  itself 
to  us  as  an  end  absolutely  speaking,  it  must  be  a  power  of 
choice  of  means  which  are  adapted  to  attain  the  end  in  view. 
Now  such  liberty,  or  immunity  from  necessity,  may  be  con- 
sidered either  as  it  affects  action  itself,  or  as  it  affects  the 
object  of  action.  So  we  can  conceive  of  two  cases  :  first,  if 
the  will  is  not  determined  to  action,  rather  than  the  absence 
of  action,  or  vice  versa — such  a  state  being  called  by  the 
Scholastics  liberty  of  exercise,  or  contradiction — and, 
secondly,  if  the  will  can  desire  one  or  other  object  of  action 
indifferently,  a  state  known  as  liberty  of  specification — or  if 
the  objects  are  contraries,  of  contrariety.  An  example  of 
the  first  is  that  of  a  man  who  is  free  to  walk  or  not  to  walk  ; 
of  the  second,  of  one  who  is  free  to  walk  to  one  place  or 
another. 

History  of  the  Problem. 

Such  are  the  preliminary  notions  which  are  necessary  if  we 
are  to  deal  with  this  problem  with  any  lucidity  ;  for  to  state 
a  question  clearly  is  often  to  go  a  long  way  in  providing  the 

1  Ci.  Summa  Theol.,  I,  83,  a.  4. 


THE  INTELLECTUAL  APPETITE  277 

solution  of  it.  That  it  has  not  been  found  easy  to  make  such 
a  statement  will  be  seen  if  we  glance  at  the  attempts  which 
philosophers  have  made  to  deal  with  it.  The  first  to  treat  it 
professedly  was  Socrates,  who  pointed  out  that  man  desires 
only  the  good,  from  which  he  concluded  that  if  he  wills 
what  is  evil,  this  must  arise  from  ignorance.  Such  evil 
desires  will  therefore  not  be  truly  voluntary,  so  that  in  a 
sense  he  is  not  free,  being  determined  by  knowledge.  Though 
Plato,  by  saying  that  only  true  science  is  invincible,  while 
opinion  is  a  kind  of  ignorance  which  leaves  the  will  free  to 
follow  it  or  not,  modifies  the  Socratic  doctrine  considerably, 
this  consideration  does  not  really  come  to  grips  with  the 
problem,  but  only  makes  it  less  difficult  to  continue  to 
believe  in  freedom. 

Aristotle,  though  '  he  did  not  examine  the  problem  very 
thoroughly,'1  is,  nevertheless,  a  decided  opponent  of  both 
the  Socratic  and  Platonic  point  of  view,  since,  as  he  points 
out,  a  man  must  be  held  morally  responsible  for  his  opinions, 
'  for  what  appears  good  to  him,'  since  he  is  responsible  for 
his  moral  state  ;  for  if  he  is  not,  virtue  is  no  more  voluntary 
than  vice.2  So  he  cannot  agree  with  the  saying  of  Socrates, 
'  No  man  is  willingly  bad  '  ;  even  if  his  badness  be  attributed 
to  his  having  an  opinion,  and  not  science,  with  regard  to  the 
point  in  question. 

Though  none  of  these  theories  go  very  deep  into  the 
question,  yet  they  were  of  great  importance  as  pointing  out 
that  the  centre  of  the  problem  is  to  be  found  in  the  nature 
of  the  judgements  which  precede  choice  ;  and  in  this  way. 
contributing  to  an  exact  statement  of  the  problem. 

The  Christian  Doctors,  generally  speaking,  assumed  the 
existence  of  freewill  in  man,  but  as  they  tried  to  investigate 
its  nature  they  gradually  led  up  to  a  clear  understanding  of 
the  meaning  of  the  question  :  '  Is  man  endowed  with  free- 
will ?  '  which  is  formally  put  by  S.  Thomas  Aquinas.3  The 
preoccupation  of  S.  Augustine,  and  many  of  these  thinkers, 

1  Cf.  Ross,  Aristotle,  p.  201. 

2  Cf.  Ethica  Nic,  Bk.  Ill,  Ch.  V,  11^3-1115*3. 

3  Summa  Theol.,  I,  Q.  83,  a.  1.  For  the  history  of  the  problem  in  the 
preceding  centuries  cf.  Lottin,  La  theorie  du  libre  arbitre  depuis  S.  Anselme 
jusqu'a  S.  Thomas  D'Aquln.     (Publications  de  la  Revue  Thomiste.) 


278         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

was  rather  with  the  difficulty  of  reconciling  freewill  with 
grace,  and  Divine  prescience,  than  with  the  strictly  philo- 
sophical question  as  to  the  nature  and  existence  of  liberty. 

Passing  to  modern  times,  we  are  faced  in  the  seventeenth 
century  with  an  intellectualist  determinism,  or  denial  of  free- 
dom, whose  first  representative  is  Spinoza.  Applying  to 
philosophy  the  methods  of  mathematics,  which  takes  no 
account  of  efficient  and  final  causes,  he  consequently 
eliminates  these  from  philosophy,  and  holds  that  the  same 
necessity  rules  in  the  realm  of  being  as  in  that  of  quantity, 
and  that  all  things  exist  by  reason  of  the  mathematical 
necessity  of  the  Divine  nature,  no  choice  being  possible  to 
God.  The  seventeenth  century  also  gave  birth  to  another 
form  of  determinism,  that  of  Leibniz,  which  is  known  as 
Psychological  Determinism.  In  his  view,  the  last  practical 
judgement,  which  ends  a  deliberation,  is  indifferent  in  the 
sense  that  it  is  contingent,  i.e.  that  the  contrary,  or  at  least 
the  contradictory,  judgement  is  possible,  inasmuch  as  it 
does  not  imply  a  contradiction  ;  but  not  in  the  sense  that  a 
man,  in  such-and-such  circumstances,  and  being  mentally 
disposed  in  a  particular  way,  could  form  the  contrary  or 
contradictory  judgement.  To  admit  this  would  be,  in  Leib- 
niz's opinion,  to  deny  the  principle  of  sufficient  reason. 
Hence  this  last  practical  judgement  is  not,  as  Spinoza  would 
have  it,  necessary  as  a  conclusion  of  geometry  is,  but  is  neces- 
sary with  a  moral  necessity. 

This  intellectualism  and  determinism  was  followed  by  a 
voluntarist,  and  indeterminist,  reaction  initiated  by  Kant, 
who,  in  the  realm  of  Ethics,  to  which  metaphysics  is  to  be 
subordinate,  introduced  the  supremacy  of  the  will  over 
reason  ;  an  idea  which  was  carried  much  further  by  subse- 
quent thinkers. 

Summary  of  Opinions. 

Thus  we  see  that  two  extreme  opinions  confront  one 
another  :  absolute  determinism,  which  holds  that  the  will  is 
always  necessitated  by  something  extrinsic  to  itself,  and 
absolute  indeterminism,  which  considers  that  it  is  entirely 
autonomous,  its  determination  not  arising  from  determinate 


THE   INTELLECTUAL  APPETITE  279 

rational  judgements,  but  incalculably,  from  its  own  hidden 
depths.  The  reasons,  in  obedience  to  which  it  appears  to 
act,  are  thus  not  the  true  determining  causes  of  its  actions, 
but  only  '  excuses,'  put  forward  to  make  it  appear  rational ; 
the  real  determination  coming  entirely  from  the  will  itself. 
Such  a  view  as  this  last,  even  in  a  modified  form,  seems,  how- 
ever, to  destroy  that  liberty  which  it  is  intended  to  safeguard  ; 
since,  if  the  reason  is  not  guiding  and  dominant  we  shall 
really  be  acting  on  blind  impulse,  either  by  instinct,  or  under 
the  influence  of  urges  which  are  perhaps  inherited  from  our 
ancestors,  and,  at  any  rate,  are  not  under  our  own  individual 
control ;  since  the  only  thing  we  can  even  profess  to  control 
is  what  is  known  to  us,  i.e.  our  rational  judgements.  More- 
over, if  our  analysis  of  the  nature  of  will  is  correct,  it  is  essen- 
tially a  rational  appetite  ;  dependent,  therefore,  on  reason, 
and,  through  it,  on  the  senses  ;  the  reason  itself  being 
dependent  on  these.  So  everything  which  influences  the 
reason  will  also  influence  the  will  as,  e.g.,  suggestion,  training, 
circumstances  and  so  on.  This  view  is  entirely  consonant 
with  our  experience  of  free  acts,  since  we  do,  in  fact,  deter- 
mine such  actions  in  accordance  with  the  motives  which  are 
put  before  us.  It  agrees  also  with  our  conception  of  freedom 
of  the  will ;  for  we  call  a  man  obstinate  or  pig-headed,  rather 
than  strong-willed,  who  sticks  to  a  course  of  action  which  is 
clearly  shown  to  be  unreasonable  ;  while  the  strong-willed 
man  is  one  who  does  not  falter  in  carrying  out  a  resolution, 
formed  after  due  deliberation,  but  who  is  '  open  to  reason,' 
as  we  say.  Such  a  man  will  modify  his  action  if  good  reason 
for  doing  so  be  shown  him. 

It  would  be  desirable,  though  it  is  not  possible  in  a  short 
summary  such  as  this,  to  review  the  development  of  the 
intellectualist  and  anti-intellectualist  points  of  view,  up  to 
the  time  when  they  meet  in  an  identification  of  liberty  and 
necessity  ;  the  first  maintaining  that  whatever  is  right,  is  ; 
and  the  second  that  whatever  is,  is  right.1 

But,  perhaps,  enough  has  been  said  to  suggest  that  both 
eliminate  freedom,  intellectualism  denying  it  outright  ;   and 

1  Cf.  Garigou-Lagrange,  Dieu,  5e  ed„  pp.  595-601.  Sorley,  Moral 
Values  and  the  Idea  of  God,  pp.  394-423.     (C.U.P.,  1924.) 


280         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

anti-intellectualism  by  implication,  since  it  is  not  we,  by  the 
use  of  reason,  but  the  facts,  the  push  of  nature,  the  '  elan 
vital,'  or  what  not,  which  are  the  masters  of  the  situation. 

Arguments  in  Favour  of  Liberty. 

Let  us  then  pass  on  to  see  what  positive  grounds  there 
may  be  for  asserting  that  we  have  the  power  of  choice,  being 
necessitated,  neither  by  some  external  force  of  circumstance, 
nor  yet  by  some  internal  force,  whether  of  nature,  making  us 
subject  to  natural  necessity,  or  of  motive,  necessitating  us 
psychologically. 

We  have  already  seen  that  the  will  cannot  be  subject  to 
compulsion  ;  and  it  only  remains  to  enquire  whether  it  is 
necessitated  from  within.1  At  this  stage,  with  the  object  of 
making  clear  the  Thomistic  argument  for  liberty,  we  shall  take 
it  for  granted  that  the  will  is,  as  we  have  already  asserted  it  to 
be,  the  rational  appetite,  thus  subordinated  to  the  intelligence : 
'  Voluntas  consequitur  intellectum.'2  We  shall  have  occasion 
later  to  discuss  this  more  fully.  Proceeding  on  this  basis, 
then,  S.  Thomas  following  the  lead  given  by  Plato  and 
Aristotle  looks  for  the  source  of  liberty,  or  immunity  from 
necessity,  in  that  faculty  which  guides  and  directs  the  will, 
viz.  the  reason.  Liberty  will  indeed  be  impossible  if  the 
judgement  of  the  reason  which  immediately  precedes  the 
definite  act  of  willing  is  determined  of  itself,  without  the 
intervention  of  the  will ;  whereas,  if,  at  this  moment,  it  is  of 
itself  indifferent  or  contingent,  it  will  leave  the  will  free  to 
follow  it  or  not.  Obviously,  that  judgement  which  is,  in  fact, 
acted  upon  must  be  a  determinate  one  ;  but,  as  we  shall  see, 
this  determination  comes  to  it,  not  from  the  reason  as  such 
but  from  the  will,  or  rather  the  whole  man. 

Freedom,  then,  must  be  conceded  to  us  in  the  degree  in 
which  the  judgement  which  precedes  and  guides  our  choice 
is,  considered  in  itself,  indifferent ;  for,  in  this  case,  since  it 
is  in  essence  indifferent,  its  final  determination,  removing 
this  indifference,  will  come  to  it,  not  from  itself,  but  from 
something  else  ;  otherwise  it  would  give  itself  a  perfection,  a 

1  Cf.  Summa  Theol.,  1.19,3  ;   59,3  ;   83,1  ;   De  Malo,  Q.  6,  A.  1. 

2  Summa  Theol.,  1.19,1. 


THE  INTELLECTUAL  APPETITE  281 

determination,  which  it  did  not  itself  possess.  That  this 
judgement,  so  considered,  is  indeed  indifferent,  is  seen  if  we 
consider  that  man,  being  in  possession  of  the  idea  of  good  in 
general,  i.e.  of  that  which  perfects  him,  is  able  to  compare 
the  particular  goods  presented  for  his  acceptance  with  this 
general  idea.  So  the  state  of  affairs,  just  before  the  moment 
of  coming  to  a  decision,  is  as  if  he  said  to  himself  :  '  What  I 
desire,  since  it  is  that  which  perfects  me,  is  good,  total  good  ; 
whereas  this  object  which  is  put  before  me,  e.g.  a  sum  of 
money,  is  good  and  not  good,  according  to  the  aspect  in 
which  I  consider  it  ;  and  consequently  I  am  not  bound  to 
desire  it,  but  I  desire  it  from  one  point  of  view,  though  not 
from  another.'  This  form  of  reasoning  (which  no  doubt  is 
rarely,  if  ever,  explicit)  represents  truly  the  state  of  mind  of  a 
man  immediately  before  his  determinate  decision  and  shows 
that  the  foundation  of  liberty  is  in  the  intellect,  which  knows 
the  nature  of  good,  and  whose  judgement  is,  consequently, 
indifferent  when  confronted  with  any  object,  or  any  act, 
which  is  not  devoid  of  all  evil  or  imperfection.  This  judge- 
ment, being  in  itself  undetermined,  cannot  therefore  determine 
the  will  ;  and,  if  it  be  true  that  what  guides  the  will  is  the 
intellect,  it  remains  undetermined  by  anything  outside  itself, 
and  so  has  mastery  over  its  own  act,  or  is  free.  Clearly,  this 
derivation  of  the  freedom  of  the  will  from  the  indifference  of 
the  intellect  only  holds  good  for  those  who  admit  that  the 
intelligence  is  of  a  different  nature  to  the  senses.  The 
Empiricist,  who  reduces  all  ideas  to  sensible  images,  and  so 
denies  the  possibility  of  forming  a  universal  judgement, 
containing  under  itself  many  particulars,  must  also  neces- 
sarily deny  liberty  to  man.  As  S.  Thomas  says  :  '  Pro  tanto 
necesse  est  quod  homo  sit  liberi  arbitrii  ex  hoc  ipso  quod 
rationalis  est.'1  He  is  guided,  not  by  natural  law,  as  a 
stone  is  in  falling,  nor  by  instinct,  like  the  animals,  but,  in 
virtue  of  the  universal  range  of  his  intellect,  he  can  compare 
the  particular  good  presented,  with  universal  good,  so  that 
he  is  not  determined  by  the  object  but  by  himself.  Thus, 
we  see  that  the  immediate  source  of  liberty  is  the  universality 
of  the  will,  resting  on  the  universality  of  the  intellect  in 

1  Cf.  Summa  Theol.,  1,83,1. 


282         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

action,  which  is  a  consequence  of  its  universal  nature,  of  its 
spirituality.  So  that,  in  the  last  resort,  it  is  the  fact  that 
man  is  a  spiritual  being  which  causes  him  to  be  a  free 
one. 

Before  we  turn  to  the  consideration  of  the  way  in  which 
man  so  determines  himself,  we  may  mention  some  other 
reasons  which  confirm  our  conclusion  that  he  does  so.  In 
the  first  place,  it  is  clear  that  to  deny  freedom  is  to  run 
counter  to  an  absolutely  universal  opinion,  for  even  those 
who,  in  their  speculations,  deny  it,  nevertheless  always  leave 
these  behind  when  they  go  out  into  the  world,  and  behave  as 
if  they  were  free.  The  idea  of  moral  responsibility  is  universal 
also,  but  how  can  a  man  be  held  morally  responsible,  and 
worthy  of  praise  or  blame,  who,  in  fact,  is  bound  to  follow  a 
certain  course  of  action,  who  is  a  prisoner  in  chains  which 
bind  his  very  soul  ? 

What  purpose,  again,  could  advice  serve  if  we  were  unable 
to  revise  a  judgement  we  had  formed,  and  so  act  in  a  different 
way  to  that  which  we  at  first  intended  ?  Moreover,  by 
introspection  we  see  that  we  do  indeed  '  make  up  our  minds,' 
as  we  say,  how  to  act  ;  at  the  very  moment  of  action  we 
can  change  our  decision,  and  even  while  action  is  in  progress 
we  can  cease  from  acting,  or  even  begin  to  act  in  a  contrary 
way. 

The  Limits  of  Liberty. 

If,  then,  we  have  such  freedom,  what  are  its  limits  ? 
First,  in  order  to  have  freedom  at  all,  we  must  have  liberty, 
both  from  compulsion  by  an  extrinsic  cause,  and  from 
necessity  or  determination  arising  from  our  intrinsic  nature, 
since  actions  which  proceed  from  our  nature  as  men  are  not 
under  our  power.  What  nature  bids  us  will  we  cannot  but 
will,  whereas  it  is  essential  to  a  free  act  that  we  should  have 
power  over  it.  Such  unloosing  of  bonds  as  this  is  evidently  a 
minimum  requirement  for  freedom,  but,  in  fact,  it  is  not 
enough,  if  we  are  really  to  have  mastery  over  our  acts.  We 
must  here  introduce  a  distinction  which  we  shall  find  useful 
more  than  once,  that  between  active  and  passive  indifference. 
By  active  indifference  we  mean  the  power  to  produce  or  not  to 


THE  INTELLECTUAL  APPETITE  283 

produce  certain  acts,  while  by  passive  indifference  we  mean 
merely  the  capacity  for  receiving  various  determinations. 
Bearing  this  in  mind,  we  see  at  once  that  freedom  implies 
active,  and  not  merely  passive  indifference,  for  a  passive 
capacity  cannot  exert  mastery,  being  potentially  at  least, 
under  the  dominion  of  that  which  determines  it.  Active  in- 
difference must  then  be  added  to  the  minimum  requirement 
for  freedom.  Nor  is  this  all,  for  we  have  seen  that  the  object 
towards  which  the  will  is  directed  must  be  such  as  does  not 
determine  its  action,  and  the  subject  which  wills  must  be  such 
that  it  can  will  or  not  will  an  object.  So,  again,  in  our 
minimum  requirement  we  must  include  both  objective  and 
subjective  indifference,  of  which  the  first  will,  of  course,  be 
present  if  the  object  is  not  wholly  desirable,  but  contains 
good  and  bad  elements,  and  the  second,  where  the  subject 
has  the  power  of  choice. 

Such  being  the  minimum  of  indifference  which  is  required 
if  there  is  to  be  freedom  at  all,  we  may  naturally  ask  also 
what  is  the  maximum  of  liberty  which  is  possible.  It  appears 
from  the  analysis  we  have  made  of  freedom  that  there  can 
be  no  liberty  of  specification  except  with  regard  to  particular 
goods  which  have  not,  at  the  moment  of  willing,  an  evidently 
necessary  condition  with  the  acquisition  of  total  good,  since 
it  is  clear  that  total  good,  or  entire  happiness,  must  be  pre- 
ferred to  all  else  ;  there  being  no  aspect  of  it  which  can 
appear  displeasing  to  us.  Hence  when  it  is  presented  to  us, 
if  we  will  at  all,  we  must  will  this,  and  cannot  will  anything 
else  ;  so  that  here  we  retain  liberty  of  exercise1  only.  Even 
this  liberty  is  very  limited,  for  though  it  is  true  we  can  judge 
that  it  is  better,  at  any  given  moment,  not  to  consider  our 
complete  happiness,  or  to  consider  it,  yet,  at  the  same  time, 
we  cannot  will  anything  whatsoever  without  virtually 
desiring  to  be  happy.  Thus,  on  the  one  hand,  there  must  be 
active  indifference  in  the  will  in  order  that  there  may  be 
liberty  at  all ;  but,  on  the  other,  liberty  of  specification  is  by 
no  means  always  to  be  found  in  free  acts,  often  we  have 
liberty  of  exercise  only.  Such  freedom  as  this,  however,  is 
sufficient  to  ensure  that  the  will  should  be  free,  and  never 

1   Vide  p.  276. 


284  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

disappears  entirely,  except  in  the  case  of  intuitive  knowledge 
of  absolute  good. 

Within  these  limits,  then,  we  may  take  it  as  established 
that  we  have  freedom,  in  so  far  as  we  are  not  determined 
either  by  our  own  nature  or  by  the  object  itself,  since  the 
final  judgement  of  a  deliberation  is,  considered  in  itself, 
indifferent,  inasmuch  as  it  presents  the  object  to  the  will  as 
partially  desirable  and  partially  undesirable. 

Views  on  the  Nature  of  Liberty. 

Is  anything  more  than  this  indeterminate  judgement 
required  in  order  that  we  may  actually  choose  ?  This 
question  brings  us  to  the  discussion  of  the  views  which  are 
taken  as  to  the  nature  of  liberty.  These  are,  in  fact,  of  two 
opposing  kinds,  for,  on  the  one  hand,  we  have  those  who  say 
that  human  liberty  consists  in  this,  that  since  the  final 
practical  judgement  relates  to  a  partial  good  the  will  is  in  no 
way  necessitated  by  it,  and  so,  where  the  intellect  judges 
that  two  objects  are  equally  good,  or  even  that  one  is  less 
good  than  the  other,  the  will  can,  without  further  direction 
by  the  intellect,  choose  either  of  the  two  equally  good 
objects  ;  or  even,  in  the  other  case,  that  which  is  judged  to 
be  less  good.  This  view  of  liberty,  known  as  liberty  of 
indifference  or  equilibrium,  has  been  held  by  many  eminent 
Catholic  thinkers,  notably  by  the  Molinists  and  Suarez,  as 
well  as  by  Scotus.  On  the  other  hand,  in  resolute  opposition 
to  this  opinion,  that,  in  the  last  resort,  the  election  made  by 
the  will  is  not  dependent  on  the  motives  put  before  it  by  the 
reason,  we  find  the  adherents  of  Psychological  Determinism 
who  say  that  it  is  impossible  to  explain  how  an  absolutely 
undetermined  cause,  such  as  the  will  is,  in  the  Molinist  view, 
can  produce  a  determination.  As  Leibniz  himself  says  : 
They  '  (i.e.  the  Molinists)  '  were  asked  not  only  how  it 
would  be  possible  to  know  to  what  an  absolutely  undeter- 
mined cause  would  determine  itself,  but  also  how  it  would  be 
possible  that  there  should  not  finally  emerge  from  it  a  deter- 
mination of  which  there  would  be  no  cause.'1  Nevertheless, 
Leibniz,  and  his  followers,  maintain  that  human  action  is 

1  Leibniz,  Essays  on  Theodicy,  I,  Sect.  48. 


THE  INTELLECTUAL  APPETITE  285 

still  free,  inasmuch  as  it  deals  with  objects  which  are  in 
themselves  contingent,  so  that  it  is  possible  to  conceive  with- 
out contradiction  of  a  man  acting  in  a  way  different  to  that 
in  which  he  does,  in  fact,  act ;  though,  at  the  same  time,  he 
cannot,  at  any  given  moment,  choose  to  act  in  either  one  or 
other  of  two  contrary  ways,  since  he  is  predetermined  to 
act  in  one  only  by  '  an  infinity  of  great  and  small  internal 
and  external  movements,  which  for  the  most  part  pass 
unnoticed.'1  The  conception  of  liberty  presented  thus  by 
Leibniz  is  that  of  a  purely  theoretical  liberty  :  in  fact,  all  the 
actions  of  our  lives  from  the  cradle  to  the  grave  could  not  be 
otherwise  than  they  are,  being  predetermined  in  the  states 
which  immediately  precede  them,  and  so  follow  necessarily 
from  them  ;  though  they  are  not  themselves  necessary 
events,  but  contingent  ones.  That  this  is  Leibniz's  meaning 
is  seen  from  the  fact  that  in  dealing  with  divine  foreknow- 
ledge he  is  able  to  dispense  both  with  the  '  scienta  media  '  of 
the  Molinists,  and  the  divine  decrees  of  the  Thomists,  and 
maintain  that  God  foreknows  free  acts,  solely  in  the  causes 
which  will  produce  them.  They  must,  then,  be  pre- 
determined in  these  causes. 

If  we  now  turn  to  the  opinion  of  the  Thomists  on  this 
question,  we  find  them  in  partial  agreement  and  partial  dis- 
agreement with  both  parties  ;  for  they  agree  with  the  Molin- 
ists that  freedom  is  destroyed  if  the  will,  at  the  moment  of 
choice,  is  determined  either  to  act,  or  not  to  act,  by  causes 
outside  its  control,  whether  these  be  rational  considerations 
or  internal  dispositions  ;  while  they  agree  with  Leibniz  that 
it  is  impossible  that  the  will,  faced  by  two  equal  goods 
should  choose  one  rather  than  the  other,  unless  some  new 
motive  intervenes.  They  maintain,  therefore,  that  nothing 
is  willed  unless  it  is  first  known  as  suitable  to  the  subject, 
that  an  uncaused  determination  of  the  will  is  impossible  ; 
and  along  with  this,  that  the  last  practical  judgement  of 
the  reason  is  not  determined  in  itself,  so  that  the  will  must 
intervene  in  order  to  determine  it.  Thus  they  wish  to 
uphold,  as  against  Scotus,  the  principle  of  intellectualism, 
the  subordination  of  the  will  to  the  reason  ;  and,  as  against 

1  Ibid.,  Sect.  46. 


286         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

Leibniz,  the  determination  of  the  reason  by  the  will.  They 
think,  moreover,  that  adherence  to  both  these  propositions 
is  forced  upon  us  by  the  analysis  of  the  act  of  choice,  and  not 
by  any  consideration  of  expediency. 

Nevertheless,  at  first  sight,  it  seems  as  if  this  position  were 
an  impossible  one.  Thus  Suarez  contends  that  these  two 
propositions  are  mutually  incompatible,  since  the  act  of  the 
will  which  determines  the  practico-practical  judgement  must 
itself  be  determined  by  another  judgement,  in  virtue  of  our 
principle  :  '  Nil  volitum  nisi  precognitum  ut  conveniens,'  and 
one  which  is  determined  in  itself,  since  we  cannot  have  an 
infinite  series  of  these  subordinated  acts  of  the  will  and  the 
intellect.  Thus,  since  we  maintain  liberty  to  be  a  fact,  we 
must  abandon  our  assertion  that  the  will  follows  the  lead 
of  the  intellect  always,  and  assent  to  his  theory  of  liberty  of 
equilibrium.  So  he  does  not  hesitate  to  write  :  '  Si  voluntas 
in  omnibus  sequatur  ductum  intellectUs  destruitur  libertas.'1 

He  therefore  considers  that  if  we  cling  to  the  principle  of 
intellectualism,  we  are  driven  to  determinism,  while  if  we 
allow  that  the  will  itself  determines  the  judgement  of  the 
intellect,  we  must  accept  the  theory  of  liberty  which  he 
favours,  and  abandon  intellectualism.  The  Leibnizians  would 
agree  with  this  view  that  there  is  no  middle  road  between  the 
indeterminism  of  the  liberty  of  equilibrium  and  their  own 
psychological  determinism. 

The  Answer  to  Indeterminism.  Liberty  of  Equilibrium 
Excluded. 
Eminently  logical  though  this  verdict  appears  to  be,  the 
answer  to  it  will  be  found  in  the  very  principles  of  intellec- 
tualism itself,  of  which  the  first,  viz.  that  all  the  acts  of  the 
will  are  formally  determined,  or  specified,  by  the  intellect, 
seems  almost  too  clear  to  need  justification.  For  how  can 
the  will,  which  is  of  its  essence  not  cognitive,  know  any  good 
and  so  be  attracted  to  it,  unless  the  good  is  first  put  before  it 
by  a  faculty  which  does  know.  The  will  cannot  judge  what 
is  practically  preferable,  since  it  has  no  knowledge  at  all,  of 
itself  :   it  must  depend  on  the  intellect  for  knowledge  of  the 

1  Cf.  Suarez,  Dis-putationes  Metaphysicce,  Disp.  XIX,  Sec.  6. 


THE   INTELLECTUAL  APPETITE  287 

characteristics  of  the  objects  presented,  and  for  judgement 
that  one  is  practically  preferable  to  another.  This  judgement 
cannot  be  given  in  favour  of  the  less  good  of  two  objects,  nor 
yet  for  one,  or  other,  of  two  which  the  intellect  judges  to  be 
equally  good.  If,  then,  it  must  be  given  for  the  better,  it  is 
the  intellect  which  formally  determines  or  specifies  the  will 
which,  as  has  been  well  said,  is  like  a  blind  man  who  uses  the 
eyes  of  a  paralytic  in  order  that  he  himself  may  walk,1  as  he 
might  do  by  pushing  him  in  a  Bath-chair.  Though  we  may 
use  such  a  simile  as  this,  it  is  worth  while  reiterating  the 
warning,  already  given,  against  succumbing  to  the  tendency 
to  which  we  are  so  prone — the  tendency  to  substantialise,  or 
even  personify,  our  faculties.  For  the  truth  of  the  matter  is 
that  man  by  his  intellect  moves  himself  to  will,  and  by  his 
will  moves  himself  to  understand.  Unless  this  essential 
unity  of  the  subject  be  always  borne  in  mind,  we  cannot 
hope  to  understand  the  interplay  of  the  faculties.  The  will, 
then,  being  non-cognitive  or  blind  cannot  see  for  itself  which 
of  two  actions  is  better,  but  must  have  its  object  put,  as  it 
were,  into  its  mouth,  when  it  will  find  it  desirable  and  be 
attracted  to  it.  But,  it  will  be  urged,  this  is  plain  deter- 
minism, for,  in  this  case,  it  is  not  the  will  itself  which  chooses, 
but  its  choice  is  already  determined  for  it  by  the  intellect, 
independently  of  it.  If  it  were  true  that  the  intellect  comes 
to  its  determination  independently  of  the  will,  the  conclusion 
would  certainly  follow  ;  but  it  is  not  true,  for  we  are  here 
dealing  with  a  judgement  concerning  what  is  desirable,  here 
and  now,  for  a  particular  man,  not  what  is  theoretically 
desirable  in  the  abstract ;  and  it  follows  that  no  decision 
can  be  come  to  as  to  this,  without  taking  into  account  the 
whole  concrete  state  of  the  man  by  whom  the  particular 
object  is  to  be  desired.  So  S.  Thomas,  and  the  Thomists, 
constantly  assert  that  this  practico-practical  judgement, 
unlike  speculative  ones,  derives  its  truth,  not  from  con- 
formity with  the  thing,  but  from  conformity  with  the  sane 
or  healthy  appetite.  Now  man  is  a  being  whose  will  is,  of  its 
very  nature,  directed  towards  the  plenitude  of  goodness, 
towards  absolute  good,   and  so  no   extraneous  influence, 

1  Sertillanges,  S.  Thomas  d'Aquin,  Vol.  II,  p.  231. 


288         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

whether  of  reason,  passion,  or  habit  can  force  it  to  desire 
any  particular  good.  These  influences  will  incline  it  in  one 
direction  rather  than  another,  but  can  never  necessitate  it. 
Thus  the  very  constitution  of  human  nature  dictates  that 
the  intellect  should  specify,  and  formally  determine,  the  will, 
since  this  latter  is  blind ;  and  that  the  will  itself  should 
determine  the  judgement  of  the  intellect  with  respect  to  what 
it  desires  here  and  now  ;  the  intellect  by  itself  being  able  to 
judge  only  in  the  abstract,  and  so  to  form  an  interdeter- 
minate  judgement  ;  so  that  the  man  can  only  say  :  '  This 
in  the  abstract  appears  preferable  '  ;  not,  '  This  is  to  be 
desired  by  me  here  and  now,'  which  can  only  be  settled  by 
the  will  which  desires. 

We  are  not,  however,  at  the  end  of  our  difficulties,  for  if 
the  intellect  must  determine  the  act  of  the  will  and  the  act 
of  the  will  must  determine  the  judgement  of  the  intellect,  we 
seem  to  be  involved  in  a  vicious  circle.  This  is  not  so, 
nevertheless,  for  it  is  one  and  the  same  act  of  the  will  which 
determines  the  practical  judgement,  and  is  itself  determined 
by  it,  though  in  different  respects.  This  all  happens  instan- 
taneously, so  that  it  is  not  the  will  which  first  determines 
the  intellect,  and  then  the  intellect  the  will,  nor  vice  versa. 
There  is  no  priority  of  time  of  one  determination  to  the  other, 
but  both  occur  simultaneously.  It  is  a  case  of  the  mutual 
causality  so  often  spoken  of  by  Aristotle,  and  the  axiom  : 
'  causes  which  are  causes  of  one  another  belong  to  different 
genera  of  causality,'  finds  its  application  here.  So  we  have 
seen,  in  Cosmology,  that  matter  determines  form  by  limiting 
it  and  making  it  individual,  while  at  the  same  time  form 
determines  matter,  limiting  it  and  making  it  specific.  Simi- 
larly, the  soul  moves  and  determines  the  body,  giving 
direction  to  its  actions  ;  and  the  body,  at  the  same  time, 
moves  the  soul,  determining,  by  its  physical  constitution, 
i.e.  here  and  now  in  the  concrete,  how  these  actions  are  to  be 
carried  out.  In  the  same  way,  mental  ability  is  required  in 
order  to  learn,  and  learning  increases  mental  ability.  This 
mutual  anteriority  of  two  causes  to  one  another  is  to  be 
found  wherever  there  is  life,  and  indeed,  wherever  there  is 
movement,  as  by  running  an  engine  it  becomes  less  stiff,  and 


THE  INTELLECTUAL  APPETITE  289 

by  becoming  less  stiff  it  is  helped  to  run.  Here,  then,  at  the 
point  when  the  last  practico-practical  judgement  is  about  to 
be  made,  the  will  applies  the  intellect  to  judge  determinately 
what  is  to  be  done,  and  receives  thereby  from  this  determinate 
judgement,  so  instantaneously  formed,  the  guidance  and 
determination  of  the  intellect  in  choosing  that  this  is  to  be 
done.  This  may  perhaps  be  compared  to  the  action  of  the 
driver  of  a  motor  car,  who  switches  on  his  headlights  in 
order  to  see  where  to  steer  the  car,  and  in  doing  so  his  motion 
receives  formal  determination  from  the  light  which  he  him- 
self has  caused.  Thus  the  last  judgement  is  not  merely  and 
wholly  intellectual,  but  contains  a  large  admixture  of 
volition  ;  for  if  of  the  two  partial  goods  proposed  in  the 
deliberation  which  thus  ends,  the  will  chooses  one  ;  it  only 
does  so,  and  puts  an  end  to  the  deliberation,  when  one  or 
other  of  these  goods  sufficiently  appeals  to  it,  and  suits  its 
taste,  for  it  to  be  satisfied  with  it.  The  goodness  of  the 
object  is  judged  in  relation  to  the  appetite  which  it  attracts. 
We  thus  avoid  altogether  the  vicious  circle  in  which  we 
seemed  to  be  involved,  and  with  it  the  theory  of  liberty  of 
equilibrium  ;  for  we  can  and  indeed  must  affirm,  that  just 
as  an  artist  cannot  work  unless  he  first  determines  his 
action  by  the  idea  of  the  work  to  be  executed,  so  the  will 
cannot  act  unless  it  first  be  determined  by  the  intellect,  so 
that  in  all  its  actions  it  follows  the  lead  of  the  intellect,  and 
therefore  the  liberty  of  equilibrium  is  at  once  excluded.  And, 
similarly,  just  as  the  artist's  idea  does  not  exercise  its  deter- 
mining effect  on  his  action,  unless  he  actually,  by  acting, 
uses  it  as  directive  in  his  action,  so  the  determination  of  the 
intellect  is  only  effective  in  making  the  will  dependent  on  it, 
if  the  will  itself,  by  its  own  action,  enters  into  this  relation 
of  dependence  on  the  intellect.  The  same  act  of  volition 
which  thus  follows  the  judgement,  in  a  certain  sense  also 
precedes  it,  there  being  relative  priority,  from  different 
points  of  view,  of  the  acts  of  the  intellect  and  will,  with 
temporal  simultaneity. 


290         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

The  Answer  to  Psychological  Determinism.  The  Theory  of 
Leibniz  Excluded. 
It  still  seems,  nevertheless,  that  if  the  will  determines  the 
judgement  in  this  way,  putting  an  end  to  the  deliberation, 
it  must  do  so  because  it  is  itself  in  a  certain  determinate 
state,  and  so  could  not  choose  otherwise  :  in  such  a  way  that 
a  man  placed  twice  in  precisely  the  same  circumstances, 
which  include  both  exterior  ones  and  interior  dispositions, 
could  not,  in  one  case,  decide  to  act,  and  in  the  other  not  to 
act.  If  he  did  so,  it  appears,  his  action  would  be  without 
sufficient  reason,  unmotived,  irrational  and  so  not  human. 
We  have  only  extricated  ourselves  from  liberty  of  equili- 
brium to  fall  into  the  clutches  of  psychological  determinism. 
In  what  has  been  said,  in  setting  out  the  principles  of 
intellectualism,  the  solution  of  this  difficulty  is  already  to  be 
found,  for  though  it  is  certain  that  the  will  must  have  a 
sufficient  reason  for  determining  the  intellect,  such  sufficient 
reason  cannot  absolutely  and  infallibly  determine  it.  This 
is  clear  from  the  very  nature  of  the  will  which  is  completely 
satisfied  by,  and,  of  its  nature,  tends  towards  nothing  less 
than  the  acquisition  of  total  good.  Consequently,  no  partial 
good  can  have  an  invincible  attraction  for  it ;  and  no 
amount  of  interior  or  exterior  impulses,  so  long  as  they  are 
finite,  can  do  so.  They  will  incline  it,  perhaps  with  great 
force,  to  act  or  not  to  act,  but  can  never  necessitate  it  to  do 
one  or  the  other.  The  motive,  then,  which  is  finally  accepted 
by  the  will,  and  which  determines  it,  is  relatively  sufficient, 
i.e.  in  relation  to  the  will  itself  at  that  particular  moment, 
but  it  is  not  absolutely  sufficient  ;  seeing  that  the  range  of 
the  will  is  universal,  as  wide  as  being  itself.  When  the  choice 
is  about  to  be  made  the  will,  of  its  own  power,  deterfnines 
the  judgement,  which  thereby  determines  the  act  of  the  will. 
The  acceptance,  or  not,  of  any  particular  motive  depends, 
then,  on  the  gratuitous  motion  of  the  will,  and  this  in  turn  on 
the  state  of  the  will  at  that  moment.  The  motive  in  itself 
is  powerless  to  force  itself  upon  the  will,  and  demand  that  it 
be  accepted,  and  the  intellect,  which  can  judge  in  the 
abstract  that  such-and-such  an  action  is  advisable  or  not,  is 


THE  INTELLECTUAL  APPETITE  291 

powerless  to  decide  whether  it  is  that  one  which  is  acceptable 
to  the  will  in  the  concrete,  and  here  and  now.  This  applies 
in  all  free  acts,  acts  which  are  rational,  being  determined  by 
the  reason,  but  free,  since,  unless  the  weight  of  the  will's 
own  power  comes  to  supplement  their  force,  they  have  not, 
of  themselves,  the  power  to  attract  it  invincibly.  This  is 
clearly  seen  in  relation  to  the  act  of  faith,  where  the  reasons 
for  making  it  are  cogent ;  but  it  depends  on  the  will  itself, 
here  and  now,  whether  it  will  accept  them,  and  make  them 
its  own  reasons.  '  Qualis  unusquisque  est  talis  finis  apparet  ei, ' 
says  Aristotle,1  '  it  is  because  we  are  persons  of  a  certain 
kind  that  we  put  before  ourselves  such-and-such  an  end  '  ; 
and,  at  any  moment,  we  are  persons  of  a  certain  kind  by  the 
self-determinations  of  the  past,  and  by  the  non-necessitated 
acceptance  of  a  self-determination  here  and  now.  It  is  not 
necessitated,  since  it  does  not  satisfy  our  desires  wholly,  but 
partially  only,  so  that  it  is  in  our  power  to  accept  it,  or  turn 
aside  ;  and  thus,  if  we  accept  it,  we  determine  ourselves, 
and  are  our  own  masters  ;  which  is  to  be  free.  It  is  in  this 
very  continuous  self-determination  of  the  unified  self  that 
freedom  essentially  consists  ;  the  man,  as  a  whole,  ruling 
himself  by  reason  and  will,  determines  his  own  course  of 
conduct,  and  is  captain  of  his  soul.2  To  be  dragged  from 
such  dominion  over  himself  by  circumstances,  passion,  or 
error  is,  so  far  forth,  to  forfeit  this  dominion  ;  and  for  this 
reason,  just  as  none  would  allow  that  vacillation  and  a 
wavering  purpose  is  essential  to  liberty,  so  the  Thomists 
have  always  maintained  that  freedom  to  sin  is  no  integral 
part  of  freedom,  but  only  a  sign  of  it.  Just  as  illness  is  a 
sign  of  life,  or  a  limp  possible  only  to  one  who  can  walk,  so 
also  a  man  could  not  sin  unless  he  were  free.  A  healthy 
animal,  however,  is  more  alive  than  a  sick  one,  and  a  sinless 
man  who  masters  himself,  by  a  sane  reason  and  a  healthy 
will,  is  more  free  than  one  who  does  not ;  but  allows  himself 
to  be  dominated  by  impulses  not  so  controlled. 

It  follows  also  from  our  principles  that  a  man  who  not 
only  did  not  sin,  but  who  was  incapable  of  sinning,  would  be 

1  Ethica  Nicomachea,  Bk.  Ill,  Ch.  V,  111^23. 

2  Cf.  Sorley,  Moral  Values  and  the  Idea  of  God.  Ch.  XVII,  esp.  pp.  436  S. 


2Q2         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

free  in  the  highest  degree ;  for  we  have  seen  that  the  end 
and  object  of  the  will  is  true  good,  while  liberty  is  the  power 
to  choose  means  which  are  in  accordance  with  this  end.  It 
will,  therefore,  clearly  be  most  perfect  where  there  is  no 
power  of  choosing  means  which  are  discordant  with  the 
attainment  of  true  good,  i.e.  where  there  is  no  power  of 
sinning.  This,  the  theologians  tell  us,  is  the  state  of  those 
who  have  immediate  knowledge  of  Good  itself,  which  is  God. 
It  belongs  to  the  perfection  of  liberty,  as  S.  Thomas  points 
out,1  to  be  able  to  choose  among  different  things  which  lead 
to  the  desired  end  ;  but  to  its  imperfection  to  be  able  to 
choose  those  which  lead  away  from  it.  Where,  then,  there  is 
no  power  of  sinning  there  is  none  of  choosing  any  means 
which  will  lead  away  from  the  acquisition  of  true  good,  and 
thus  the  imperfection  of  liberty  is  eliminated  ;  its  perfection, 
or  the  power  of  choosing  among  the  means  which  will  lead  to 
it,  being  maintained.  For  just  as  when  we  wish  to  go  from 
place  to  place,  we  may  suitably  choose  to  travel  by  train,  by 
car,  on  foot,  or  by  some  other  means,  similarly,  in  seeking 
goodness  itself  we  should  be  wholly  free  in  choosing  among 
the  means  of  acquiring  it,  even  if  we  were  quite  incapable  of 
choosing  anything  which  diverted  us  from  it. 

For  freedom  of  use  does  not  imply  freedom  to  misuse  ;  and 
is  indeed  greater  in  proportion  as  the  chance  of  misuse 
diminishes.  So  a  barber  who  was  incapable  of  making  a  slip 
— if  we  can  conceive  such  a  marvel — would  use  his  razor 
much  more  freely  than  one  who  was  not ;  and,  in  fact,  with 
perfect  freedom. 

These  considerations  are  sufficient  to  show  .us  that  the 
power  to  sin  is  no  necessary  part  of  freedom  ;  its  presence 
in  us  is  a  sign,  but  still  more,  a  defect  of  liberty.  Thus  Von 
Hugel,  who  so  constantly  and  emphatically  affirmed  this 
truth  says  :  'To  be  able  to  do,  to  be,  evil  is  a  defect,  a  restric- 
tion of  liberty.  .  .  .  We  should  feel  humbled,  not  only  by 
our  actual  sins,  but  already  by  the  fact  that  we  can  commit 
such  things.'2 

1  Summa  Theologica,  I,  Q.  62,  a.  8,  ad  3. 

2  Von  Hugel,  Selected  Letters,  p.  317.  Cf.  Essays  and  Addresses  (Second 
Series),  p.  203. 


THE   INTELLECTUAL  APPETITE  293 

S.  Augustine  finely  sets  out  this  doctrine  when,  to  the 
assertion  of  Julian  that  man  could  not  be  capable  of  his 
proper  good,  unless  he  were  capable  also  of  evil,  he  replies  : 
'  Say  rather  that  man's  nature  was  first  made  capable  of 
good  and  evil,  not  that  it  could  not  become  capable  of  good 
only  ...  so  that  if  he  had  not  sinned  when  he  could  sin,  he 
would  have  come  to  that  blessedness  where  he  could  not  sin. 
For  each  is  a  great  good,  though  one  is  less,  the  other 
greater.  For  it  is  less  to  be  able  not  to  sin,  greater  not  to  be 
able  to  sin.'1 

Just  as  a  man  now  is  free,  though  unable  to  will  anything 
except  in  so  far  as  it  appears  to  be  good,  so  he  would  be 
wholly  free  if  he  could  not  will  anything  except  in  so  far  as  it 
was  in  truth  good.  It  is  for  this  reason  that  S.  Augustine 
also  says  :  '  Multo  liberius  erit  arbitrium  quod  omnino  non 
poterit  servire  peccato.'2 

There  is  one  last  point  to  which  reference  must  be  made 
before  we  close  this  consideration  of  liberty.  We  have  said 
that  the  will  in  choosing  has  a  sufficient  motive,  but  one 
that  does  not  infallibly  determine  it.  But  is  not  this  to  assert 
a  contradiction,  for  how  can  the  will  be  determined,  and  yet 
not  infallibly  determined  ?  It  seems  that  this  is  both  to  be 
determined  and  not  to  be  determined.  Now  we  have  already 
seen  that  in  order  to  account  for  movement  and  multiplicity 
we  were  bound  to  assert  the  existence  of  a  not-being,  which, 
in  a  certain  sense,  is,  viz.  potency  ;3  so  here,  the  fact  of  the 
relation  between  universal  good  and  particular  goods  forces 
us  to  assert  the  existence  of  a  determination  which  does  not 
actually  determine  us,  but  is  only  able  to  do  so.  For  it  is 
precisely  on  these  particular  goods  that  the  will  bears,  and 
since  there  is  indetermination  in  its  object,  there  must  be 
also  indetermination  in  the  will.  So  S.  Thomas'  teaching 
on  liberty  joins  up  with  the  great  central  thesis  of  his  philo- 
sophy, the  division  of  finite  being  into  potency  and  act. 
This  division  is  demanded  by  the  facts  of  multiplicity  and  of 
movement,  and  both  the  will  of  man,  and  its  objects,  must 

1  Opus  Imperfectum  contra  Julianum,  Liber  V,  LVIII.  (Opera  Omnia, 
ed.  Cong.  S.  Mauri,  Tom.  X,  939  F.) 

2  Enchiridion  Fidei,  c.  105. 

8  Cf.  Cosmology,  '  Discussions  on  Motion  and  Individuality.' 


294         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

share  in  this  indetermination  of  finite  being.  This  is  a 
doctrine  which  has  its  roots  deep  down  in  the  teaching  of 
Plato  and  Aristotle  ;  and  which  is  found  at  every  stage  of 
S.  Thomas'  presentation  of  the  '  philosophic/,  perennis.' 

It  will  be  useful  to  summarise  the  results  arrived  at  in 
this  chapter  : 

i.  Man  is  free,  since  the  judgement  presented  by  the  reason 
for  his  acceptance  is  never  absolutely  determined  in  itself, 
owing  to  the  disproportion  which  exists  between  total  good, 
the  adequate  object  of  desire,  and  the  partial  goods  which 
are  made  known  to  us  by  the  judgement. 

2.  Nevertheless,  all  the  actions  of  his  will  are  formally 
determined  by  the  judgement,  so  that  the  theory  of  liberty 
of  indifference,  or  equilibrium,  is  excluded :  the  judgement 
which  determines  the  will  owing  its  determination  to  the  act 
of  the  will  itself. 

3.  This  strange  fact  is  due  to  the  unity  of  man's  conscious 
life  ;  for  that  is  desirable  to  a  particular  man  which  suits 
his  particular  state  here  and  now.  This  can  never  be  decided 
by  the  intellect,  judging,  as  it  were,  in  the  abstract,  but  only 
by  the  concrete  desire  of  the  will. 

4.  This  concrete  self-determination  of  man  is  not  a  neces- 
sary consequent  of  his  antecedent  states,  which,  though 
affecting  him,  cannot  infallibly  determine  him  to  choose  one 
of  two  partial  goods  in  preference  to  the  other,  since  such 
goods  are  both  equally  incapable  of  satisfying  his  unlimited 
yearnings  for  absolute  good.  Thus  psychological  deter- 
minism is  excluded  by  the  domination  of  the  will  in  action, 
over  the  intellect  in  judging.  So  man,  by  his  will,  is  master 
of  his  judgement,  and,  under  the  guidance  of  judgement, 
so  mastered,  is  master  of  himself. 

Psychological  determinism  neglects  the  unity  of  the  self, 
forgetting  that  a  motive  only  becomes  a  motive  for  me  here 
and  now,  if  I  desire  it  to  be  so,  if  I  adopt  and  accept  it. 
Indeterminism,  on  the  other  hand,  makes  the  will,  an 
incalculable  force  which  interferes  with  the  guidance  of 
reason,  and  turns  it  from  its  normal  course  without  reason. 
Such  irrational  willing  could  not  be  freedom,  but  merely  the 
emergence  of  some  blind  impulse,  an  impulse  which  is  not 


THE  INTELLECTUAL  APPETITE  295 

under  the  man's  control.  In  neither  of  these  ways  can  man 
be  his  own  master,  but  only  by  the  control  of  the  will  by  the 
intellect,  and  of  the  intellect  by  the  will,  of  the  whole  man  by 
himself. 

The  more  such  freedom  is  developed  the  more  will  conflict 
and  strain  be  eliminated  ;  and,  if  its  development  were 
fully  achieved,  a  man  would  be  in  possession  of  the  un- 
fettered exercise  of  a  good  will,  whereby,  without  deviation, 
he  would  uniformly  desire  only  his  true  good  :  to  serve 
which  is  to  rule.1 

1  For  the  whole  of  this  subject  the  following  may  be  consulted  : 
Garigou-Lagrange,  Dieu,  Son  existence  et  sa  nature,  2e  partie,  Ch.  IV. 
Sertulanges,  S.  Thomas  d'Aquin,  Tom.  II,  Livre  VI,  Gh.  I— III.  Cf.  also 
Sorley,  op.  cit.,  Sect.  17.    Ward,  The  Realm  of  Ends,  Lectures  13  and  14. 


CHAPTER   XIV 

THE   NATURE   OF   THE   INTELLECTUAL   SOUL   IN   MAN 

Its  Substantiality — Its  Spirituality — It  is  the  Substantial  Form — 
Simple — And  One  Only — Differing  Specifically  from  that  of 
Other  Animals — Reasons  for  this  View. 

In  the  three  preceding  chapters  we  have  seen  something  of 
the  way  in  which  the  mind  of  man  works  ;  and  we  now  pass 
on  to  enquire  what  information  we  can  gather,  from  our 
conclusions  as  to  its  working,  with  regard  to  its  nature. 
What  sort  of  thing  is  this  mind,  or  intellectual  soul  ? 

The  phrase  '  mind  or  intellectual  soul '  by  its  very 
ambiguity  at  once  suggests  a  question  as  to  the  nature  of 
the  intellectual  principle  in  us,  viz.  is  it  merely  a  mental 
power,  or  is  it  something  substantial  ? — for  mind  may  mean 
either  mental  powers,  or  a  substantial  principle  of  such 
powers.  Our  first  question,  then,  is  whether  there  is  a  sub- 
stantial principle  of  our  intellectual  powers.  The  idea  that 
there  is  not  some  principle  which  is  capable  of  producing 
thoughts  and  retaining  them,  but  which  does  not  itself 
require  to  be  produced  or  retained  by  any  other  principle — 
in  a  word,  that  there  is  not  a  substantial  principle  of  intellec- 
tual operations — would  hardly  occur  to  common  sense. 
Nevertheless,  many  philosophers  have  held  that  there  is  in 
us  no  substantial  mind,  but  only  a  series  of  mental  acts. 
Such  a  view  must  necessarily  be  taken  by  those  who  deny 
altogether  the  possibility  of  affirming  the  existence  of  any 
substance,  as  do  the  Phenomenalists,  e.g.  Hume  and  Taine. 
In  accordance  with  this  view,  the  Associationist  Psychology 
was  developed,  to  give  some  sort  of  account  of  our  processes 
of  thinking,  and,  if  possible,  some  plausibility  to  the  idea  of 
thoughts  without  a  thinker.  Though  Associationism  finds 
little,  if  any,  acceptance  among  modern  psychologists,  the 

296 


INTELLECTUAL  SOUL  IN  MAN  297 

phenomenalist  point  of  view  is  still  prevalent.  The  denial 
of  the  substantiality  of  the  human  mind  is  not  confined  to 
the  Phenomenalists,  for  in  Monist  theories,  such  as  those 
of  Spinoza  and  Hegel,  though  the  substantiality  of  mind  is 
not,  in  a  sense,  denied,  nevertheless,  the  mind  which  they 
recognise  is  either  the  Divine  mind,  in  the  case  of  Spinoza, 
or  the  Absolute,  in  the  case  of  Hegel.  Human  minds  are  but 
an  aspect  or  phase  of  these.1  Consequently,  such  philo- 
sophies in  no  sense  allow  the  substantiality  of  the  individual 
mind  of  man. 

The  main  stream  of  philosophic  thought  has,  on  the  other 
hand,  always  considered  that  common  sense  is,  on  the  whole, 
right ;  and  so  has  recognised  that  psychic  phenomena,  such 
as  thoughts  and  volitions,  need  some  substantial  subject, 
which,  owing  to  its  capacity  for  supporting  itself,  is  enabled 
to  support  them  also.  In  the  Platonic  tradition  this  subject 
is  called  the  soul. 

This  view  of  the  matter  is  surely  true,  for  how  can  we  con- 
ceive of  thoughts,  volitions,  etc.,  which  have  no  subject  to 
support  them,  since  they  are  actions,  and  an  action  sus- 
pended in  the  void  is  quite  inadmissible.  Just  as  it  is 
impossible  to  have  motion  without  something  which  moves, 
so  also  it  is  impossible  to  have  thought  without  a  thinker,  or 
willing  without  a  subject  who  wills.  Moreover,  consciousness 
tells  us,  not  only  of  the  presence  of  thoughts  and  volitions, 
but  also  that  it  is  I  who  think,  feel,  will,  and  so  on.  Hence 
this  '  I  '  remains  permanent  beneath  the  changing  pheno- 
mena. If  I,  the  man,  am  but  a  series  of  phenomena,  with  the 
passing  of  the  phenomena,  I  should  also  pass  away.  But 
consciousness  tells  me  that  I  endure.  Thus,  to  say  :  '  I  think, 
feel,  will,'  etc.,  is  to  testify  that  there  is  not  merely  a  multi- 
tude of  thoughts,  volitions,  etc.,  but  that  there  is  a  single 
principle  of  them  all.  Further,  such  statements,  expressing, 
as  they  do,  a  most  clear  conviction  of  consciousness,  show 
that  these  phenomena  cannot  be  attributed  to  any  particular 
organ,  or  part  of  us,  to  the  exclusion  of  the  rest,  but  must  be 
attributed  to  us  as  a  whole,  i.e.  to  some  substantial  principle 
in  us. 

1  Cf .  Stace,  The  Philosophy  of  Hegel,  pp.  439  ff. 


298         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

It  might,  perhaps,  be  suggested  that  the  support  which 
such  phenomena  necessarily  require  is  merely  the  material 
organism.  This,  however,  cannot  be  true,  since  the  organism 
is  not  in  itself  a  unity,  but  is  composed  of  a  multitude  of 
diverse  parts  ;  and,  moreover,  it  is  not  fixed  and  permanent, 
but  constantly  changing,  so  that  after  a  time  it  is  entirely 
renewed.  It  follows,  then,  that  the  substantial  principle 
must  be  something  distinct  from  the  body  considered  in 
isolation,  or  that  the  soul  of  man  must  be  substantial, 
unifying  the  body. 

We  may  add  that  if  the  soul  were  nothing  but  a  succession 
of  phenomena,  memory,  the  conviction  of  the  continuity  of 
the  Ego,  and  the  feeling  of  responsibility  become  inexplicable. 
No  reason  could  then  be  assigned  why  any  thought,  feeling, 
or  desire,  should  be  connected  with  any  other.1 

If,  then,  we  recognise,  with  common  sense,  that  there  is 
in  man  a  substantial  principle  of  psychic  acts,  or  a  soul 
which  is  substantial ;  we  shall  naturally  wish  to  discover 
something  concerning  its  nature.  Such  an  enquiry  can 
evidently  be  carried  out  only  by  philosophy ;  it  is  one 
which  is  beyond  the  scope  of  experimental  science,  the  inner 
nature  of  a  substance  not  being  amenable  to  experiment. 
Hence,  experimental  psychology  rightly  excludes  such  con- 
cepts as  the  simplicity  or  spirituality  of  the  soul.  Such 
exclusion  should  not,  however,  lead  to  denying  these  or  other 
attributes  to  the  conscious  subject,  in  fact  such  a  denial 
would  be  as  much  beyond  the  sphere  of  natural  science  as  an 
affirmation  of  them  would  be. 

If  man  is  indeed  in  possession  of  intellect  and  will,  as  we 
have  maintained,  it  follows  at  once  that  the  substantial 
principle  of  these  powers  must  also  be  intellectual,  since  they 
derive  from  it.  Further,  we  have  seen  that  this  intellectual 
power  in  man  is  an  immaterial  one,  though  dependent  on 
matter — i.e.  on  the  body  and  the  senses — in  order  to  act ; 
in  other  words,  it  is  one  which  is  extrinsically  dependent  on 
matter,  though  not  intrinsically,  and  subjectively  in  its  own 
nature.    The  same,  then,  must  also  be  true  of  the  source  of 

1  So  Ward,  Psychological  Principles,  pp.  34-41,  and  McDougall,  Outline 
of  Psychology,  pp.  39  ff.,  affirm  that  we  are  obliged  to  recognise  a  '  conscious 
subject  '  as  '  an  indispensable  hypothesis.' 


INTELLECTUAL  SOUL  IN   MAN  299 

intellectual  power,  viz.  the  soul,  which  will,  therefore,  also 
be  spiritual  in  this  sense. 

The  principle  of  life  in  man,  which  we  call  the  soul,  must 
necessarily  be  of  the  nature  of  form,  that  which  makes  a 
thing  what  it  is,  since  it  is  in  virtue  of  the  soul  that  man  is  a 
living  intellectual  being  ;  and  since  it  is  substantial,  it  will 
be  his  substantial  form.  Like  all  other  substantial  forms,  it 
will  not  have  quantitative  parts  of  itself  ;  and  we  have  seen 
reason  to  believe  that  the  souls  of  the  higher  animals,  among 
whom  no  doubt  man  must  be  reckoned,  have  no  quantitative 
parts,  even  owing  to  their  union  with  the  body,  and  so  are 
indivisible.  We  should  conclude,  then,  that  the  human  soul 
is  quantitatively  simple  from  our  previous  considerations, 
but  we  have  now  learned,  in  addition  to  these,  the  fact  that 
it  is  spiritual,  and  so  must  be  unextended  ;  extension  being 
an  attribute  of  the  body,  not  of  the  spirit ;  and  consequently 
from  this  point  of  view  also,  we  are  led  to  affirm  that  the 
human  soul  is  simple.  But  even  if  the  intellectual  soul  be 
thus  in  itself  spiritual  and  simple,  it  might  be  maintained, 
it  seems,  that  there  is  more  than  one  life-principle,  or  soul, 
in  man.  A  little  reflection  will  shew  that  this  is  impossible, 
for  not  only  would  this  destroy  the  essential  unity  of  the 
individual,  since  each  life-principle  must  be  a  substantial 
form,  so  that  any  such  principle,  after  the  first,  must 
form  an  accidental  union  with  the  already  constituted  com- 
pound ;  but  also  it  is  clear  that  vegetative,  sensitive  and 
intellectual  life  mutually  help  or  hinder  one  another, 
which  could  only  be  the  case  if  they  all  proceed  from 
one  and  the  same  principle.  So  sensitive  and  vegetative 
life  are  conditions  sine  qua  non  of  intellectual  life,  and 
they,  in  turn,  are  guided  and  preserved  by  means  of  the 
intellect.  We  observe  also  that  an  intensity  of  action  in 
any  one  of  the  three  spheres  results  in  diminution  of  activity 
in  the  others  ;  thus  intense  action  of  the  senses,  or  vital 
organs,  hinders  mental  operations.  In  the  reverse  order, 
intense  mental  activity  leads  to  insensibility,  generally 
partial,  but  in  exceptional  cases,  complete  ;  as  in  the  self- 
hypnotism  practised  by  the  fakirs.1 

1  An  account  of  some  instances  of  such  self-hypnotism  is  given  by 
Dr.  William  Brown  in  Philosophy  (1931),  pp.  215  ff. 


3oo         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

So  far  we  have  considered  the  nature  of  the  soul,  in  itself 
and  intrinsically,  and  we  have  seen  that  it  is  substantial, 
spiritual,  simple,  and  not  accompanied  by  other  life- 
principles  in  a  single  individual.  We  must  now  ask  what  is  its 
relation  to  the  life-principles  in  other  animals.  Is  it  of  the 
same  kind  as  these,  or  does  it  differ  specifically  from  them, 
in  such  a  way  that  we  can  assert  that  no  animal,  other  than 
man,  has  an  intellectual  soul  ?  We  shall  be  obliged  to 
recognise  a  specific  distinction  if  we  find  that  in  the  life  of 
man  we  have  a  positive  addition  of  perfection,  or  actuality, 
and  not  merely  a  development,  or  increase,  of  powers  which 
are  possessed  by  animals  lower  in  the  scale  than  man.  It  is 
clear  enough  that  the  possession  of  intrinsic  independence 
of  matter,  as  contrasted  with  intrinsic  dependence  on  it, 
will  constitute  a  distinction  of  this  kind,  if  it  be  established  ; 
since  here  we  should  have  a  positive  addition  of  immateri- 
ality, or  of  actuality  ;  for  what  is  of  itself  dependent  on 
matter  cannot  develop  into  something  which  it  is  not,  i.e. 
something  independent  of  matter  ;  so  adding  to  itself  a 
positive  perfection  or  actuality,  for  which  it  has  no  capacity, 
and  which  is,  indeed,  excluded  by  its  very  nature. 

We  have  already  seen  the  evidences  of  such  independence 
in  man  in  his  capacity  for  forming  universal  and  so 
immaterial  concepts,  in  his  freedom,  and  in  the  unlimited 
range  and  scope  of  his  intellect.  To  these  we  may  add 
further  signs,  such  as  his  capacity  for  progress,  and  his 
power  of  speech. 

His  freedom,  as  we  saw,  is  rooted  in  his  capacity  for  com- 
paring the  particular  goods  proposed  for  his  acceptance  with 
universal  good,  and  in  the  last  resort  in  his  spirituality,  as  is 
also  the  distinctive  way  in  which  his  mind  works  in  the 
formation  of  universal  concepts.  Capacity  for  progress, 
which  man  possesses,  is  but  a  consequence  of  this,  for  it  is 
obtained  by  means  of  reflection,  envisaging  the  end  to  be 
aimed  at  in  general,  and  then  comparing  the  various  means 
which  might  be  used  to  gain  it.  Consequently,  it  is  a  sign  of 
the  universality  or  immateriality  of  that  mind  which  is  the 
source  of  progress.  The  power  of  speech  again  is  an  indica- 
tion of  the  immateriality  of  the  mind  of  the  speaker  ;    for 


INTELLECTUAL  SOUL  1^  MAN  301 

speech  is  articulated  sound,  composed  of  arbitrary  symbols 
which  are  designed  to  express  concepts.  Speech,  therefore, 
implies  that  the  speaker  has  concepts  to  express,  and  indicates 
the  existence  of  thought,  even  though  it  may  sometimes,  as 
has  been  suggested,  serve  to  conceal  thoughts. 

Do  we,  in  fact,  find  any  evidence  of  the  existence  of  these 
indications  of  intellectuality  and  immateriality  in  other 
animals  than  man  ? 

This,  no  doubt,  is  a  disputable  question  ;  and  to  answer 
it  fully  would  require  a  minute  observation  and  examination 
of  the  actions  of  all  animals.  Clearly,  such  an  enquiry  is 
far  too  extensive  to  be  undertaken  here,  if  indeed  it  can  be 
undertaken  at  all.  Nevertheless,  if  we  look  at  the  matter 
impartially,  uninfluenced  by  any  presupposition,  either  in 
favour  of,  or  against,  the  evolutionary  hypothesis,  we  shall 
see  that  there  are  a  number  of  converging  probabilities  which 
all  point  to  the  conclusion  that  animals,  other  than  man, 
have  not  that  immateriality  which  we  are  obliged  to  ascribe 
to  human  beings. 

In  spite  of  the  keen  and  wide  observation  of  animal  actions 
in  recent  years,  no  definite  evidence  of  freedom  has  been 
discovered  in  them.  Though  it  is  true  that  when  confronted 
with  particular  material  obstacles  to  action  they  may  modify 
their  action  to  some  extent,  yet  there  is  no  indication  that 
this  arises  from  any  abstract  consideration  of  the  problem, 
but  can  be  wholly  accounted  for  by  a  power  of  combining 
sense  images. 

It  is  not  in  dispute  that,  normally,  each  class  of  animal 
has  its  own  determinate  way  of  acting  which  never  varies  ; 
'  every  swallow,'  as  S.  Thomas  says,  '  building  its  nest  in  the 
same  way.'  Each  species  has  its  own  definite  mode  of 
breeding,  nesting,  and  feeding,  from  which  it  deviates  little, 
if  at  all.  There  is  thus  :  '  no  evidence  that  it  ever  does,  or 
makes  anything  according  to  a  plan  of  its  own.'1  It  shows 
none  of  the  signs  of  freedom. 

Similarly,  no  progress  is  observable  among  animals,  such 
change  as  there  is,  not  being  initiated  by  themselves,  but 

1  Cf.  Ivy  Mackenzie,  Aristotelian  Society's  Proceedings  (1927), 
pp.  275  f. 


302         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

coming  about  from  nature  and  circumstance,  not  of  their 
own  intention.  No  doubt  they  can  learn,  but  only  within 
very  narrow  limits,  in  so  far  as  they  associate  particular 
sensations  with  particular  acts.  Nowadays,  this  fact  is 
explained  by  the  theory  of  conditioned  reflexes  ;  but  what- 
ever explanation  be  accepted,  the  fact  of  their  lack  of  initi- 
ative and  progress  is  certain. 

Do  animals  speak  ?  Certainly  they  communicate  their 
emotions  to  one  another  by  cries  and  sounds  of  various 
kinds,  but  there  is  no  shred  of  evidence  that  they  have  any 
conventional  system  of  articulate  sounds  ;  in  fact,  since 
here,  again,  we  find  stereotyped  sounds  which  differ  in  each 
species  we  are  justified  in  concluding  that  their  '  speech  '  is 
fixed  for  them  by  nature,  and  not  by  themselves.  Talking 
animals  are  a  figment  of  the  imagination  of  romantic  story- 
tellers and  are  only  to  be  found  in  fairy  tales,  not  in  nature. 
The  absence  of  conventional  speech  has  the  advantage  that 
they  cannot  lie,  as  man  can. 

From  every  point  of  view,  then,  we  may  conclude  that  it 
is  as  certain  as  such  a  thing  can  be  that  animals  have  not  a 
mind  and  soul  of  the  same  immaterial  kind  as  man  has. 

If  this  be  so  we  once  more  find  ourselves  in  the  presence  of 
two  grades  of  life  which  are  distinguished  by  an  essential,  a 
specific  difference,  and  not  merely  a  difference  of  degree.  As 
living  things  differ  from  inanimate  ones,  as  animals  from 
plants,  so  also  do  men  differ  from  the  other  animals.  No 
evidence  is  forthcoming  that  animals  are  possessed  of  an 
abstractive  universalising  faculty  such  as  the  human  intel- 
lect is  ;  but  the  progress  of  investigation  shows  them,  even 
more  clearly  than  common  observation  had  done,  as  confined 
to  particular  objects  of  knowledge,  and  very  limited  in  their 
modes  of  action  even  with  regard  to  these.  That  the  higher 
animals,  at  least,  have  a  kind  of  intelligence,  no  one  would 
deny  ;  but  it  does  not  appear  to  be  of  the  kind  which  sees 
the  meaning  in  things,  but  merely  that  which  is  able  to 
observe  that  certain  objects  are  desirable  and  useful  to  them 
here  and  now.  Human  beings,  perceiving  the  meaning  of 
objects,  are  not  tied  to  the  concrete,  the  particular,  the 
material,  and  so  in  them  there  is  a  definite  increment  of 


INTELLECTUAL  SOUL  IN  MAN  303 

immateriality,  actuality  or  perfection  over  and  above  that 
found  in  the  other  animals.1 

The  intellectual  soul  of  man  is  not,  however,  divorced 
from  his  material  organism,  but  is  evidently  intimately 
connected  with  it ;  which  brings  us  to  the  question  of  the 
nature  of  this  connection. 

1  Prof.  Julian  Huxley,  though  a  decided  opponent  of  the  ideas  here 
advocated,  goes  so  far  as  to  assert  that  '  there  is  no  evidence  at  present 
that  even  the  highest  animals  possess  ideas,  or  even  images.'  (Essays  of  a 
Biologist,  Essay  II  :  '  Biology  and  Sociology,'  p.  97,  1923  edition.)  He 
quotes  in  support  of  this  view  Thorndike,  Animal  Intelligence,  New  York, 
191 1,  and  Washburn,  The  Animal  Mind,  New  York,  1913. 


CHAPTER   XV 

THE   UNION   OF   SOUL   AND   BODY   IN   MAN 

Views   on   the   Question — Monism — Psycho-physical   Parallelism — 

Accidental  and  Essential  Union — Reasons  for  the  Thomist  View 

The  Mode  of  the  Union — How  the  Soul  is  Present  to  the  Body. 

The  question  of  the  union  of  soul  and  body  is,  no  doubt, 
a  very  perplexing  one,  for  if  there  is  such  union  we  must 
assert  that  the  material  and  the  immaterial,  the  qualitative 
and  the  quantitative,  the  necessary  and  the  free  are  one. 

In  the  few  pages  at  our  disposal  we  can  give  no  adequate 
account  of  all  the  theories  on  this  subject  which  have  been 
advanced  ;  but  it  is  necessary  and  possible  to  see  what  are 
their  general  types. 

In  the  first  place,  we  may  cut  the  knot  by  denying  that 
there  is  any  union,  inasmuch  as  there  are  not  two  entities  or 
entitative  principles  to  unite  but  one  only.  This  one  may 
be  either  the  body  alone,  or  the  soul  alone  ;  the  first  being 
the  solution  of  materialistic  monism,  which  alleges  that  mind 
is  either  a  form  of  matter,  or  an  appearance  of  matter,  while 
the  second  is  the  view  of  idealistic  monism,  according  to 
which  matter,  and  body,  is  an  illusion.  In  the  materialistic 
theory,  mind  or  soul  is  something  we  construct  owing  to  our 
ignorance  of  the  workings  of  material  forces,  and  so  is  an 
illusion  like  the  dryads,  river-gods,  and  other  spiritual  forces 
which  were  supposed,  by  primitive  peoples,  to  direct  the 
operations  of  nature,  operations  which  we  now  know  to  be 
the  result  of  material  forces  only.  Idealistic  monism,  on  the 
contrary,  holds  mind  to  be  the  only  reality,  and  what  we  call 
matter  but  a  projection  or  shadow  of  mind. 

In  both  these  theories  the  problem  disappears ;  but 
neither  accords  with  common  sense,  since  no  one  would 
naturally  suppose,  either  that  thought  and  consciousness 

304 


UNION  OF  SOUL  AND   BODY  IN  MAN      305 

are  simply  some  kind  of  bodily  secretion,  nor  yet  that  he  had 
no  body  at  all.  If  it  be  recognised,  then,  that  there  are,  in 
fact,  two  realities  in  man,  body  and  soul,  it  may  still  be 
denied  that  they  are  united,  in  which  case  they  continue  in 
company,  side  by  side,  but  without  affecting  one  another. 
How  this  unfailing  concomitance  is  to  be  explained  it  is 
difficult  to  say,  but  it  seems  that  it  would  have  to  be  attri- 
buted to  some  kind  of  Pre-established  Harmony. 

These  seem  to  exhaust  all  the  possible  ways  of  solving  the 
problem  of  union  by  denying  that  body  and  soul  are  united. 
If,  then,  we  allow  that  they  are  united,  their  union  may  be 
either  essential,  if  they  form  one  nature,  or  accidental,  if 
they  merely  act  on  one  another,  while  remaining  in  them- 
selves distinct.  This  last  type  of  view  seems  very  natural 
to  us,  and  has  in  fact  been  widely  held,  both  by  ordinary 
men  and  by  philosophers,  such  as  Plato.  It  is  somewhat 
difficult  to  see  how  such  diverse  things  as  mind  and  matter 
could,  in  fact,  act  on  one  another  ;  but  the  chief  objection  to 
this  theory  is  that  it  breaks  up  the  essential  unity  of  the  self, 
so  destroying  human  nature  altogether.  If  consciousness 
tells  us  anything  about  ourselves,  it  is  surely  this,  that  we 
are  unities  ;  not  a  soul  which  is  imprisoned  in,  or  hovering 
about,  a  body  with  which  it  is  not  connected  by  nature  ;  or, 
rather,  to  which  it  is  by  nature  opposed.  Neither  body  nor 
soul  can  be  said  to  be  the  individual  man,  so  that  if  they  do 
not  form  one  nature  together,  the  man  himself  disappears. 
This  difficulty  is  expressed  in  William  de  Morgan's 
epigrammatic  lines  : 

'  John  has  a  soul.'     Upon  the  whole 
The  tombstone  lies  which  says  '  Hie  jacet.' 
But  if  John  really  has  a  soul, 
What  in  the  world  is  John  who  has  it  ? 

It  seems,  then,  that  we  are  bound  to  assert  that  soul  and 
body  together  form  one  nature  ;  that  the  union  between 
them  is  an  essential  one.  This  is  the  view  expressed  by  S. 
Thomas  and  constantly  adhered  to  by  the  Thomists,  in  spite 
of  the  fact  that  the  Platonic  view,  according  to  which  the 
soul  finds  only  a  temporary  home,  or  prison,  in  the  body  is 


306         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

clearly  more  easily  reconcilable  with  the  Christian  doctrines 
of  immortality  and  resurrection. 

Scotus,  who  followed  the  Platonic  and  Augustinian  tradi- 
tion, thought  that  there  are  in  man  two  substantial  forms, 
that  of  the  body,  the  form  of  corporeality,  which  makes  it  a 
specifically  human  body,  and  gives  it  existence  as  such  ;  and 
the  soul-form,  which  is  a  substance  in  its  own  right ;  while 
at  the  same  time  he  maintained  that  the  union  of  the  soul 
and  body  is  an  essential  one.  If  by  substantial  form  we 
mean  that  act  by  which  a  thing  is  constituted  in  its  specific 
nature  and  distinguished  from  others,  it  seems  impossible  to 
see  how  essential  unity  can,  in  this  hypothesis,  be  maintained; 
for  if  the  body  is  constituted  as  a  body  by  the  form  of  cor- 
poreality, it  cannot  be  given  its  nature  by  the  soul  since  it 
already  has  it ;  consequently,  the  soul  cannot  be  its  sub- 
stantial form,  but  must  be  an  accidental  one,  and  the  union 
will  be  accidental.  If,  on  the  other  hand,  we  do  not  mean  by 
substantial  form  that  which  gives  specific  substantial  nature 
to  a  thing,  then  we  must  acknowledge  either  that  the  body 
never  has  such  a  nature,  or  that  it  receives  it  from  something 
other  than  the  form  of  corporeality,  which  consequently  will 
be  unable  to  do  more  than  add  something  to  a  body  already 
constituted  as  a  substance ;  in  which  case  it  is  clearly  an 
accidental  form,  and  the  union  is  once  more  an  accidental 
one.  We  are,  in  fact,  back  again  in  our  old  dispute  about  the 
plurality  of  forms,  about  which  enough  has  already  been  said. 

It  is  not  our  business,  however,  to  discuss  the  Scotist 
opinion,  but  to  explain  that  which  the  Thomists  hold.  The 
latter,  both  on  the  grounds  of  observation  and  introspection, 
as  well  as  on  account  of  the  logic  of  their  system,  feel  obliged 
to  assert  that  the  body  has  no  form  of  its  own,  but  is  immedi- 
ately informed  by  the  soul,  which  is,  therefore,  not  a  com- 
plete substance,  but  the  actual  element  in  the  composite 
human  substance.  This  position,  it  may  be  noticed,  is  not 
unaccompanied  by  difficulty ;  since,  according  to  the 
fundamental  principles  of  Thomism,  it  is  impossible  to  have 
numerical  differentiation  of  any  specific  form  except  by  the 
reception  of  this  form  in  matter.  Hence,  it  seems  that  when 
union  with  the  body  ceases  at  death,  the  soul  will  either  not 


UNION  OF  SOUL  AND  BODY  IN  MAN      307 

survive  at  all,  or  if  it  does,  will  be  merged  into  a  universal 
soul,  losing  its  individuality.  S.  Thomas  was  unable  to 
accept  either  of  these  consequences,  whether  as  a  philosopher 
or  theologian,  and  he  points  out  that  the  relation  of  form 
and  matter  being  a  transcendental  one,1  which  arises  from 
the  very  nature  of  the  related  terms,  so  long  as  either  of  them 
remains  in  being,  it  will  retain  its  relationship  to  the  other.2 
If,  then,  the  soul  survives  death,  it  will  not  cease  to  be 
individual,  but  will  retain,  as  part  of  its  very  being,  that 
essential  relationship  to  the  body  which  it  had  before  its 
severance  from  it. 

In  order  to  establish  the  strictly  essential  character  of  the 
union  of  body  and  soul,  the  Thomists  point,  in  the  first  place, 
to  the  observed  actions  of  human  beings  ;  and  they  notice 
that  some  of  them  are,  in  their  origin,  common  to  both  soul 
and  body.  Such  are  anger,  fear,  and,  in  general,  the  emotions, 
as  well  as  all  sensation,  since,  as  we  have  seen,  this  is  organic, 
and  so  only  possible  as  proceeding  from  body  and  soul  in 
conjunction.  Now,  though  it  is  true  that  two  principles  of 
action  might  produce  a  single  resultant  action,  as  the  motion 
of  a  wagon  might  be  the  single  result  of  the  pull  of  two  or 
more  horses,  yet  it  is  impossible  that  one  and  the  same  action 
should  issue  from  more  than  one  source  of  action,  since  the 
action  of  a  thing  is  the  consequence  of  its  powers  and  so  of 
its  form  ;  so  the  two  essentially  distinct  principles  of  action, 
two  forms,  must  produce  actions  which  are  also  distinct, 
though  they  may  combine  in  a  common  effect.  Hence  a 
single  common  operation  cannot  proceed  from  two  essen- 
tially distinct  principles,  and  emotion  and  sensation,  being 
such  operations,  their  principle,  the  human  being,  must  also 
be  essentially  one. 

Further,  similar  considerations  to  those  which  led  us  to 
conclude  that  animals  are  essential  unities  will  be  applicable 
to  the  case  of  man.  For  here,  again,  we  find  that  all  the 
operations  of  mind,  and  of  the  several  organs  of  the  body, 
tend  to  the  preservation  and  well-being  of  the  organism,  or 
individual,  as  a  whole  ;    the  parts  of  the  body,  under  the 

1  Cf.  S.  Thomas,  Contra  Gentiles,  II,  c.  81. 
*  Cf.  Vol.  II,  General  Metaphysics. 


308         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

influence  of  life,  adjusting  their  actions  in  such  a  way  that 
the  normal  functioning  of  the  organism  as  a  whole  may  not 
be  impaired.  If,  then,  both  bodily  and  mental  actions 
naturally  tend  to  the  well-being  of  the  whole  man,  rather 
than  to  that  of  any  particular  part ;  not  to  their  own  good, 
but  to  the  good  of  the  whole,  we  are  justified  in  concluding 
that  this  is  due  to  the  fact  that  man  himself,  body  and  soul, 
is  a  single  nature,  an  essential  unity.  For  the  natural 
tendencies  of  a  thing  are  but  the  expression  of  its  nature,  so 
that  the  end  to  which  a  thing  tends  must  correspond  to  the 
principle  of  its  operations,  which  is  its  nature.  If,  therefore, 
various  operations  all  tend  constantly  to  a  single  end,  this 
must  be  because  it  is  their  nature  to  do  so,  which  nature 
must  thus  be  common  to  them  all,  and  so  a  single  remote 
principle  of  them  all. 

We  may  here  mention  very  briefly  some  further  considera- 
tions which  strengthen  our  conclusion.  In  the  first  place, 
we  attribute  all  our  actions,  whether  of  mind  or  body,  to 
one  and  the  same  self  ;  and  say  :  '  /  think,  love,  hear,  see, 
feel,  grow,'  and  so  on.  Consciousness,  therefore,  bears 
testimony  to  the  fact  that  soul  and  body  form  a  single  nature. 
Again,  we  fear  death,  the  dissolution  of  the  union  of  body 
and  soul,  a  fact  which  finds  no  ready  explanation  if  soul  and 
body  are  joined  only  accidentally,  or  not  joined  at  all,  as 
Psycho-physical  Parallelism  suggests.  According  to  these 
theories,  it  seems  that  we  should  '  dread  the  grave  as  little 
as  our  bed  ' ;  but  we  do  not,  and  if  our  thesis  is  correct, 
ought  not  to  do  so. 

The  modern  alternative  to  our  theory  is  that  of  parallelism, 
which  denies  the  causal  influence  of  mind  on  body,  and  vice 
versa.  Both  these  denials  are  faced  by  grave  difficulties,  for 
if  body  does  not  act  on  mind,  how  are  we  to  account  for 
sensation,  which  is  certainly  mental  ?  On  the  parallelist 
theory,  it  must  arise  from  some  mental  cause,  and  no  such 
cause  is  discoverable,  either  in  my  own  previous  mental 
states — for  which  among  them  can  cause  me  to  have  sensa- 
tion, e.g.,  of  some  sudden  sound  ? — nor  in  the  action  of  any 
other  mind.  Again,  if  mind  does  not  act  on  body,  we  must 
deny  the  influence  of  thought  and  volition  on  our  bodily 


UNION  OF  SOUL  AND  BODY   IN  MAN      309 

movements,  such  as  walking,  which  seems  fantastic  ;  and 
all  handicrafts,  and  artificially  constructed  articles  must 
be  attributed  simply  to  bodily  motions  without  any  inter- 
vention of  thought  or  intention.1 

It  will  be  seen  that  though,  from  one  point  of  view,  the 
Thomist  theory  of  the  union  of  mind  and  body  may  be  called 
an  interaction  theory,  in  so  far  as  each  exerts  causal  influence 
on  the  other  ;  nevertheless,  since  they  are  said  to  be  united 
in  a  single  nature,  such  causality  is  not  to  be  understood  as 
that  of  two  complete  beings,  of  different  kinds,  on  one 
another ;  as  would  be,  for  example,  the  action  of  a  pure 
spirit  on  a  material  object.  Soul  and  body  are  so  interwoven 
that  there  is  something  of  the  body  in  the  nature  of  the  soul, 
and  something  of  the  soul  in  the  organisation  of  the  body. 
Human  nature  is  something  greater  than  either  soul  or  body, 
and  embraces  them  both.  This  idea  is  emphasised,  and 
worked  out,  in  the  view  which  the  Thomists  hold  as  to  the 
mode  of  their  union,  for  they  consider  that  the  soul  is,  of  its 
nature  and  without  any  intermediary,  the  substantial  form 
of  the  body. 

It  is  clear  that  it  must  be  the  body's  substantial  form,  and 
not  an  accidental  one,  if  the  two  are  to  form  one  nature,  this 
being  the  very  meaning  of  substantial,  or  essential,  union  as 
opposed  to  accidental.  Moreover,  it  is  by  the  soul  that  man 
is  made  a  living,  sentient  and  intellectual  being  ;  and  so,  by 
it,  he  is  constituted  in  his  specific  nature  and  distinguished 
from  others,  to  do  which  is  the  office  of  substantial  form. 
Again,  it  is  the  principle  of  being,  which  also  is  due  to  sub- 
stantial form  ;  for  in  living  things  to  live  is  to  be,  and  since 
the  soul  is  the  principle  of  life,  it  is  also  that  of  being.  It  is 
also  the  principle  of  action,  for  human  actions  are  vital  ones, 
and  the  soul,  as  the  life-principle,  is,  therefore,  their  source  ; 
and  so  the  substantial  form  in  man. 

Neither  can  there  be,  in  addition  to  the  soul,  some  sub- 
stantial form  which  informs  the  body,  as  such  ;  and  which 
is  subsumed  under  the  form  which  is  the  soul,  for  we  have 

1  Space  does  not  allow  of  a  full  discussion  of  these  theories,  but  the 
reader  may  be  referred  to  Broad,  The  Mind  and  its  Place  in  Nature,  pp. 
113-117  ;  McDougall,  Modern  Materialism,  Ch.  Ill  ;  Hobson,  The  Domain 
of  Natural  Science,  pp.  67,  355  f.  ;    Driesch,  Mind  and  Body. 


310         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

seen  that  it  is  impossible  to  retain  essential  unity  if  there  is 
more  than  one  substantial  form1  since  the  first  form  would 
constitute  the  body  as  a  substance,  so  that  it  could  not  be 
made  so  by  the  soul,  which,  therefore,  could  add  to  it  no 
substantial,  or  essential,  perfection,  but  only  an  accidental 
one  ;  and  so  would  be  joined  to  it  accidentally.  The  same 
consideration  also  applies  to  the  view,  recently  put  forward, 
that  the  chemical  elements  in  the  body  retain  their  own 
specific  natures,  and  so  their  own  substantial  forms,  even 
when  they  are  parts  of  man's  body.  If  this  were  so,  a  man 
would  be  a  mere  conglomeration  of  material  elements,  all 
essentially  distinct,  but,  in  some  unexplained  way,  under  the 
influence  of  the  soul.  There  can  be  no  question  of  there  being 
such  a  thing  as  human  nature  in  this  case  ;  nor,  since  the 
chemical  elements  must,  a  pari,  be  also  considered  as  essen- 
tially composite,  of  any  specific  chemical  nature ;  but  all 
those  differences  in  kind  which  we  thought  we  found  in  the 
world  of  nature  will  be  done  away  with.  So  true  is  it  that 
unless  we  preserve  essential  unity  we  cannot  have  essential 
diversity  :  the  many  are  impossible  without  the  one.  Again, 
we  are  at  the  very  heart  of  the  Thomistic  view  of  the  universe, 
which  refuses  to  reject  the  many  for  the  one,  or  the  one  for 
the  many ;  but,  in  the  successive  increments  of  actuality 
which  it  observes  to  be  added  to  the  potentiality  of  matter 
in  the  ascending  scale  of  material  things,  clings  firmly  to 
variety  in  unity,  specific  variety  in  the  unity  of  being,  and 
individual  variety  in  the  unity  of  species.  The  only  alterna- 
tive to  this  view  they  consider  to  be  some  form  of  Monism  ; 
all  things  being  either  some  undifferentiated  matter,  or  all 
some  undifferentiated  form  or  act.  It  is  because  they  reject 
with  all  possible  emphasis,  on  the  basis  both  of  experience 
and  consciousness,  such  views  as  these,  that  they  insist  so 
untiringly  on  the  unity  of  form  in  the  individual. 

If,  then,  we  admit  that  the  soul  is  the  one  substantial  form 
of  the  body,  giving  their  specific  nature,  as  human,  to  all  its 
parts,  we  see  at  once  the  mode  of  its  presence  to  the  body  ; 
since  it  must  be  clearly  be  present  to  the  whole  body,  making 
it  human,  and  to  each  part  of  it.    The  whole  of  it  must  thus 

1  Cf.  Cosmology,  Ch.  X,  Q.  i,  pp.  129  fi. 


UNION   OF   SOUL  AND   BODY  IN  MAN      311 

be  present  in  the  whole  body,  and  in  each  and  every  one  of 
its  parts — in  contradistinction  to  the  way  in  which  one 
extended  thing  is  present  in  another,  e.g.  when  a  bottle  is 
filled  with  beer,  the  whole  of  the  beer  is  in  the  whole  bottle, 
but  not  in  each  part  of  it.  It  does  not  follow  that  all  the 
soul's  powers  are  exercised  in  each  part  of  the  body.  In 
fact  it  is  obvious  that  this  is  not  the  case,  for  the  soul  cannot 
exercise  the  whole  of  its  power  in  every  part  of  the  body, 
as  the  legs  cannot  be  used  for  seeing,  or  the  eyes  for  hearing  ; 
while  no  part  of  the  body,  nor  the  whole  of  it,  is  fitted  to  be 
the  instrument  of  intellectual  operations,  of  thinking  and 
willing. 

Such  essential  presence  is,  evidently,  not  circumscriptive, 
a  mode  of  location  which  belongs  only  to  bodies  ;  nor  yet 
definitive  by  means  of  operation,  since  the  union  of  soul  and 
body  is  essential,  but  definitive  by  means  of  information  ;x 
so  that  the  soul  is  tied,  by  its  very  nature,  to  the  place  which 
the  body  occupies,  and  cannot,  at  the  same  time,  be  also  in 
another  place. 

1  Cf.  Cosmology,  Ch.  VI,  Sect.  I,  esp.  pp.  81  f. 


CHAPTER  XVI 

THE   ORIGIN  AND   DESTINY  OF  THE   HUMAN   SOUL 

Origin — Not  by  Generation  or  Emanation,  but  by  Creation — The 
Transmigration  of  Souls — The  Thomist  View  of  the  Succession 
of  Forms  in  the  Individual — Immortality — Opinions — Reasons 
for  Thomist  View — The  Metaphysical  Argument. 

The  soul,  then,  is  spiritual  and  simple,  and  yet,  at  the  same 
time,  it  has  an  essential  relation  to  the  body,  forming  one 
nature  with  it.  What  light  do  these  conclusions  throw  on 
its  origin  and  destiny  ? 

First,  with  regard  to  its  origin,  we  observe  that  the  soul  is 
a  form,  and  a  special  kind  of  form,  viz.  a  spiritual  one  : 
which  is  independent  of  matter  in  its  nature  ;  so  that  this 
nature  cannot  have  been  derived  from  matter.  In  the  case 
of  the  forms  of  other  animals,  where  this  special  considera- 
tion did  not  apply,  we  saw  that  it  was  not  necessary  to  postu- 
late any  other  cause  of  them  than  the  vital  powers  of  the 
parents ;  so  that  their  generation  belongs  entirely  to  the 
material  order ;  but,  in  the  case  of  man,  this  cannot  be  so, 
since  that  which  is  generated  is  a  being  which,  as  far  as  its 
form  is  concerned,  is  a  spiritual  one.  The  cause,  then,  of  a 
human  being  must  be  at  least  as  spiritual  as  this  being 
itself.  Such  a  cause  might  be  either  the  child's  parents,  or 
God.  As  for  the  parents,  they  are  doubtless,  in  any  event, 
the  cause  of  the  child's  coming  to  be,  for  even  if  they  do  not 
generate  the  soul,  they  do  produce  the  body  which  is  essen- 
tially related  to  it ;  and  since  the  term  or  result  of  any 
generative  process  is  neither  matter  nor  form  in  disjunction 
from  one  another,  but  the  compound  of  the  two,  that  agent 
will  properly  be  said  to  generate  the  compound  which  is 
the  cause  of  uniting  a  new  form  with  matter.  This  is  pre- 
cisely what  the  parents  do,  since  by  forming  a  body  which  is 

312 


THE  HUMAN  SOUL  313 

fitted  to  receive,  and  actually  requires  a  human  soul  to 
inform  it,  they  cause  the  union  of  matter  and  form  to  come 
about.  It  is  not  necessary,  therefore,  in  order  to  maintain, 
as  we  certainly  must,  that  parents  generate  their  own  child, 
to  say  that  they  produce  its  soul  from  their  own  sub- 
stance. In  fact,  if  we  were  to  suppose  that  they  did  so,  we 
should,  if  we  grant  that  the  soul  is  immaterial,  find  ourselves 
in  an  impossible  position.  It  seems  quite  clear  that  it  could 
not  be  produced  by  their  purely  physical  or  bodily  powers, 
since  it  has  a  nature  of  a  higher  order  than  these.  Nor  yet 
could  it  be  produced  by  their  souls  or  spiritual  powers,  since 
the  souls  of  the  parents  are  indivisible.  Since  they  have  no 
parts,  the  souls  of  the  children  could  not  be  parts  of  them, 
or  divided  off  from  them  by  emanation.  Thus,  the  spiritu- 
ality of  the  human  soul  debars  us  from  saying  that  it  is 
produced  by  the  parents.  It  appears,  then,  that  its 
production  must  be  due  to  some  other  spiritual  cause. 
We  might  conceive  such  a  cause  bringing  the  soul  into 
being  either  by  emanation  from  itself,  or  by  way  of 
creation  ;  i.e.  making  it  to  be,  without  drawing  it  out 
of  itself,  or  of  any  other  pre-existing  being.  The  emana- 
tionist  hypothesis  cannot  be  entertained  for  the  reason 
just  given,  viz.  that  spiritual  beings  are  indivisible,  and 
so  cannot  separate  anything  from  their  own  substance 
by  way  of  emanation.  It  might  be  suggested  that  an  infinite 
being  of  this  kind  could,  without  such  separation  or  in  other 
words,  with  the  entirety  of  its  being,  be  itself  the  spiritual 
principle  of  all  men.  This  idea,  apart  from  the  fact  that  it  is 
clearly  pantheistic,  is  excluded  by  the  other  aspect  of  the 
human  soul,  the  fact  that  it  is  the  form  of  the  individual 
man,  and  so  limited  and  finite,  as  the  correlative  of  a  finite 
body.  Consequently,  it  could  not  also  be  an  infinite  spirit. 
No  other  hypothesis,  therefore,  remains,  with  regard  to  the 
origin  of  the  human  soul,  than  the  creationist  one.  We  shall 
see  later  that  such  an  act  of  creation,  the  absolute  beginning 
and  production  of  some  being,  cannot  be  effected  by  any 
finite  cause  ;  and,  if  this  be  true,  we  must  conclude  that 
human  souls  are  created  by  an  infinite  spiritual  being.  Such 
an  infinite  being  is  commonly  called  God.     The  Scholastics 


314         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

are  thus  in  general  agreement  in  asserting  that  the  human 
soul  comes  into  existence  by  means  of  creation  by  God. 

Even  if  this  be  accepted,  we  should  wish  to  know  when  this 
'  infusion  '  of  the  soul  into  the  body,  this  coming  into  it 
'  from  without,'  of  which  Aristotle  speaks,1  takes  place. 

The  doctrine  that  the  soul  is  the  form  of  the  body,  so  having 
an  essential  relation  to  this  individual  body,  and  to  this  only  ; 
excludes  two  notions  as  to  the  way  in  which  it  comes  to  be 
in  it,  viz.  by  metempsychosis,  and  by  passing  into  it  after  a 
previous  existence.  The  first  view,  the  theory  of  the  trans- 
migration of  souls,  has  been,  in  the  past,  very  widely 
accepted  ;  and  even  to-day  is  held  by  many,  as  by  the 
Theosophists  and  the  Hindus.  Plato  took  over  the  idea 
from  Pythagoras,  who  may  himself  have  derived  it  from 
Orphism.  It  maintains  that  one  soul  may  pass  through 
many  bodies,  both  of  animals  and  men.2  If,  however,  it  be 
true  that  soul  and  bodv  really  form  one  nature,  standing  to 
one  another  in  the  relation  of  potentiality  to  act,  it  will  be 
impossible  for  a  soul,  or  act,  which  is  thus  essentially  related 
to  one  body,  to  become  essentially  related  to  another, 
without  parting  with  something  essential  to  it,  and  so,  at 
least  breaking  its  actual  continuity.  In  fact,  it  cannot  so 
change  essentially,  being  a  simple  nature  or  form,  and  must 
therefore  continue  to  be  related  to  one  body,  and  one  only. 
The  doctrine  of  transmigration  is,  therefore,  compatible 
with  Platonism,  where  the  union  of  the  soul  and  body  is 
looked  on  as  accidental,  but  not  with  Aristoteleanism,  in 
which  the  body  derives  its  nature  from  the  soul,  giving  to  it, 
in  turn,  individuality.  Such  a  relationship  as  this  can, 
evidently,  not  be  destroyed  so  long  as  the  soul  continues  in 
existence.  The  supposition  that  the  soul  exists  before  the 
body  is  also  seen  to  be  gratuitous  and  bizarre,  if  their 
relationship  is  such  as  S.  Thomas  holds  it  to  be  ;  for  the 
soul's  natural  being  is  in  the  body,  and  if  it  existed  before  its 

1  De  Generatione  Animalium,  II. 3  ;  736b28.  Aeiirerai  34  rbv  vovv  ixbvov 
Ovpadev  iireiaiivaL  kclI  Oelov  elvai  ixbvov. 

2  Cf.  Taylor,  Plato  :  The  Man  and  his  Work,  p.  308  ;  Stace,  Critical 
History  of  Greek  Philosophy ,  p.  217.  See  also  the  interesting  account  of  the 
history  of  the  doctrine,  and  of  the  light-hearted  way  in  which  it  was 
treated  by  Plotinus,  in  Dean  Inge's  Philosophy  of  Plotinus,  Vol.  II,  pp.  29- 
36. 


THE  HUMAN  SOUL  315 

union  with  the  body  it  would  do  so  in  a  state  of  frustration, 
unable  to  fulfil  its  natural  function  ;  and  without  any 
spiritual  or  intellectual  activity,  such  as  it  would  have  if  it 
continues  to  exist  after  separation  from  the  body,  since  it 
would  not  naturally  have  acquired  any  knowledge  in  the 
pre-existing  state.  Under  these  conditions  it  seems  almost 
impossible  to  attach  any  definite  meaning  to  the  question  : 
did  the  soul  exist  before  the  body  P1 

S.  Thomas,  as  is  fairly  generally  known,  held  a  view  of  a 
contrary  kind,  viz.  that  what,  by  a  process  of  evolution, 
becomes  the  human  body  existed,  prior  to  its  becoming  so, 
in  the  two  lower  orders  of  life,  the  vegetative  and  the  sensi- 
tive. Beginning  its  life  with  a  vegetative  form  or  soul,  as 
organisation  increases  and  advances  far  enough  to  make  the 
foetus  capable  of  sensitive  activity,  a  corruption  and  a 
generation  taking  place,  the  body  receives  a  sensitive,  and 
with  further  development  an  intellectual,  or  human,  soul.2 
He  thus  admits  specific  evolution,  or  development,  within 
the  individual,  under  the  influence  of  a  higher  power,  i.e. 
human  life,  or  the  souls  of  the  parents  ;  these  in  turn,  as  he 
points  out,3  being,  like  all  the  activities  and  powers  of  nature, 
subordinated,  as  instruments,  to  the  power  of  God.  The 
principle  which  leads  to  this  view  is  that  matter  must  be 
proportionate  to  its  form,  and  so,  in  this  case,  the  body  must 
be  sufficiently  organised  to  be  a  fitting  correlative  of  the 
intellectual  soul,  before  it  is  informed  by  it.  Whatever  may 
be  thought  of  the  truth  of  this  view,4  it  no  doubt  harmonises 
well  with  the  modern  way  of  envisaging  the  development  of 
life  through  the  ages  ;  though  embryology  seems  to  show 
that  sensitivity  is  present  in  the  human  foetus  very  early,  if 
not  from  the  start. 

Whether  we  accept  this  view,  or  hold  that  the  soul  is 
infused  at  the  moment  of  conception,  our  conclusion  that 

1  Cf.  S.  Thomas,  Contra  Gentiles,  Lib.  II,  Chaps.  83  and  84. 

2  Summa  Theol.,  I,  Cj.  118,  a   2,  ad  2. 

3  Contra  Gentiles,  II,  Ch.  89. 

4  For  a  discussion  of  it  from  a  philosophical  point  of  view  cf.  Hugon, 
Cursus  Philosophies  Thomistica,  Vol.  Ill,  pp.  199  ff.  Its  theological 
aspect  is  dealt  with  in  the  Diet,  de  Theologie  Catholique ,  art.  "  ame,"  Vol.  I, 
Cols.  1306  ff.,  and  Vol.  VII,  Col.  846.  Cf.  also  Mercier,  Psychologie,  Vol.  II, 
PP-  339-34°- 


316         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

the  parents  really  generate  their  children,  will  not  be 
affected,  since  the  earlier  life-principles  will  be  but  forms 
whose  raison  d'etre  is  to  lead  up  to,  and  prepare  for  the 
coming  of,  the  human  soul.  Thus  in  either  view  the  parents 
prepare  the  body,  and  make  it  proportionate  to  this  soul. 

We  can,  then,  take  it  as  proved  that  the  human  soul 
originates  by  means  of  creation,  and  is  not  produced  by  any 
kind  of  conception  of  it  by  the  parents,  whether  spiritual  or 
physical ;  and,  further,  that  it  does  not  exist  before  union 
with  the  body  ;  though  the  supposition  that  it  does  so  does 
not  seem  to  be  absolutely  impossible.  Moreover,  it  does  not 
pass  from  body  to  body,  since  it  is  the  form  of  this  particular 
body.  What,  then,  becomes  of  it  when  it  is  separated  from 
the  body  at  death  ?  Does  it  cease  to  exist  altogether  ?  So 
we  find  ourselves  brought  naturally  to  the  question  of  the 
immortality  of  the  human  soul,  a  question  which,  like  that 
of  liberty,  and  for  a  similar  reason,  has  always  been  in  the 
forefront  in  philosophical  discussions  :  for  it  is  vital  to  us, 
and  not  merely  a  matter  of  curiosity,  to  give  an  answer  to  it. 

We  shall,  therefore,  not  attempt  to  give  an  account  of 
the  history  of  this  question  of  survival,  as  this  is  impractic- 
able in  a  short  space  ;  but  it  is  necessary  to  glance  at  some 
of  the  principal  answers  to  the  questions  :  can  and  will  the 
soul  survive  death  ? 

First,  there  are,  of  course,  those  who  deny  the  possibility 
of  survival  altogether,  inasmuch  as  they  think  that  life  is 
essentially  of  the  material  order,  and  simply  disappears  when 
the  organism  ceases  to  function  normally.1  Few,  perhaps, 
adopt  an  attitude  quite  so  intransigent  as  this,  but  rather 
say  that  it  is  more  probable  that  life  altogether  disappears 
at  death.  These  profess  to  hold  this  only  as  an  opinion,  but 
actually  they  hold  it  so  tenaciously  that  it  is,  for  them,  rather 
certain  than  probable.2  If,  on  the  other  hand,  it  is  allowed 
that  there  is  some  survival  after  death,  we  find  no  agreement 

1  So  one  of  the  materialists  picturesquely  asserted  that  it  is  as  im- 
possible for  the  soul  to  exist  without  the  body  as  it  would  be  for  the  flame 
of  a  candle  to  exist  without  the  candle. 

2  Cf.  E.  S.  P.  Haynes,  The  Belief  in  Personal  Immortality.  In  spite  of 
his  profession  of  open-mindedness,  it  seems  clear  the  author  regarded  the 
belief  as  an  illusion. 


THE  HUMAN  SOUL  317 

as  to  its  nature  ;  and  in  particular  there  is  a  great  difference 
of  opinion  on  the  question  whether  such  survival  is  a  per- 
sonal or  impersonal  one.  It  may,  perhaps,  be  said  roughly 
that  those  who  do  not  adhere  to  the  Platonic  and  Christian 
tradition,  as  Spinoza,  hold  the  latter  view,  while  Christian 
philosophers  adhere  to  the  former.  It  is  further  supposed  by 
some  that  those,  who  in  life  devote  themselves  to  material 
and  temporal  interests,  will  cease  to  be  when  these  interests 
cease,  while  those  who  live  the  higher  life  of  the  spirit  will 
survive.    '  We  are  what  we  love  and  care  about.'1 

The  Thomistic  doctrine  is  very  definite,  for  it  regards  the 
soul  of  every  human  person  as  being  of  its  nature  indestruc- 
tible, so  that  survival  does  not  depend  on  its  own  activities 
during  life  ;  and,  moreover,  since  it  is  also  by  nature  a  finite 
form,  it  must  survive  as  such  ;  and  so,  not  as  absorbed  into 
the  divinity,  or  in  any  collective  fashion. 

In  support  of  their  contention,  modern  Thomists  use 
arguments  of  many  different  kinds  ;  which  may  perhaps  be 
grouped  under  two  heads,  moral  and  metaphysical.  Such 
is  the  general  agreement  of  mankind  as  to  the  fact  of  sur- 
vival, a  belief  which  is  found  at  all  times  and  in  all  races ; 
the  necessity  for  the  rigorous  enforcement  of  the  moral  law, 
or  the  supremacy  of  the  good  and  the  true  over  evil  and 
irrationality. 

This  last  argument  must  take  the  form  that  the  purpose 
of  the  moral  life  is  unattainable  if  death  extinguishes  life 
entirely.  If,  then,  we  recognise  the  absolute  claim  of 
morality,  so  that  we  feel  certain  that,  whatever  fails,  right 
must  endure  and  prevail,  we  shall  be  forced  to  recognise 
survival  after  death  as  the  necessary  condition  for  the  fulfil- 
ment of  this  claim.  No  one  who  perceives  at  all  clearly  the 
fundamental  notions  of  Thomism  will  be  in  any  doubt  as  to 
the  conclusions  a  Thomist  must  come  to  as  to  the  perman- 
ence and  absolute  claim  of  moral  good  ;  for,  as  we  have  seen 
all  along,  the  intellect  is,  in  their  view,  of  its  nature  directed 
to  nothing  less  than  being  as  such,  the  entire  range  of 
reality  ;  and  the  will  satisfied  with  nothing  less  than  infinite 
good.     Such  good  is  permanent  if  anything  is,  and  being 

1  Inge,  The  Philosophy  of  Plotinus,  Vol.  II,  p.  25. 


318  MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

infinite,  unattainable  under  the  finite  conditions  of  this  life. 
Again,  it  is  central  in  the  philosophy  of  S.  Thomas  to  judge 
of  the  nature  of  a  thing  from  the  end  to  which  it  tends,  or,  in 
S.  Thomas'  phrase,  by  its  '  natural  desires.'  Such  desires 
cannot  be  fruitless,  incapable  of  satisfaction,  for  if  they  were 
the  nature  which,  as  a  nature,  tends  towards  their  fulfilment, 
would  clearly  be  tending  to  nothing  and  so  not  towards  their 
fulfilment.  It  would  therefore  be  and  not  be  that  nature. 
Desire,  moreover,  follows  and  is  proportionate  to  knowledge, 
so  that  since  man  by  his  intellect  grasps  universal  and  per- 
petual being,  and  so,  of  his  nature,  desires  it,1  such  perpetual 
existence  must  be  attainable  by  him.2  Such  arguments  as 
these,  no  doubt,  need  much  fuller  development  than  we  are 
able  to  give  them  here  if  they  are  to  strike  the  mind  with 
their  full  force  ;  but  even  in  this  skeleton  form  it  can  be 
seen  that  they  are  not  lightly  to  be  dismissed.3 

Let  us  now  turn  to  the  argument  which  is  par  excellence 
the  metaphysical  argument  for  the  immortality  of  the  soul. 

We  must  first  consider  the  ways  in  which  anything  can  be 
corrupted  or  destroyed.  This  may  come  about  owing  either 
to  some  extrinsic  or  some  intrinsic  cause  of  corruption.  It 
comes  from  intrinsic  corruption  when  there  are  in  the  thing 
warring  elements  which  seek  to  oust  one  another  from  it,  or, 
at  least,  dissociable  elements.  Examples  of  the  first  are  to 
be  found  in  gasses  which  remain  stable  only  under  the 
influence  of  some  external  force,  or  pressure  ;  of  the  second 
in  all  chemical  compounds.  Another  type  of  intrinsic  cor- 
ruption is  that  which  occurs  as  a  consequence  of  something 
on  which  there  is  dependence  being  corrupted  ;  as  the  sight 
fails  when  the  eye  is  injured,  or  a  picture  is  destroyed  if  the 
canvas  rots.  Now  neither  of  these  modes  of  corruption  can 
affect  the  human  soul ;  for  since  it  has  no  parts,  whether 
quantitative,  since  it  is  not  extended  ;  or  essential,  since  it  is 
form  only  and  not  a  compound  of  form  and  matter,  it  is 

1  On  this  question  of  natural  desire  Fr.  O'Mahoney's  book,  The  Desire 
of  God  in  the  Philosophy  of  St.  Thomas  Aquinas,  may  be  consulted  with 
much  profit. 

2  Cf.  Contra  Gentiles,  L.  II,  Chaps.  55,  59  ;   Summa  Theologica,  1.76,6. 

8  For  a  lucid  and  full  exposition  of  the  first  argument  cf.  Taylor,  The 
Faith  of  a  Moralist,  Series  I,  Lect.  7,  pp.  281  ff. 


THE   HUMAN  SOUL  319 

obvious  it  cannot  have  any  contrary  or  dissociable  elements 
within  it,  and  so  is  immune  from  the  first  kind  of  corruption. 
It  is,  in  fact,  impossible  to  suppose  that  the  unifying  prin- 
ciple should  not  be  itself  a  unity.  This  indeed  applies  to 
all  forms,  which  are  all  of  them  acts,  and  not  a  compound  of 
act  and  potency,  and  yet  we  have  seen  that  some  of  these 
are  divisible  with  the  division  of  the  matter  which  they 
inform.  This  second  kind  of  corruption  and  division  cannot, 
however,  affect  the  human  soul,  for  as  we  saw  again,  it  does 
not  depend  on  the  matter  which  it  informs  for  its  existence, 
but  being  in  itself  immaterial  or  spiritual,  exists  in  its  own 
right  and  independently.  A  material  thing  is  corrupted 
when  its  form  is  separated  from  matter,  but  an  immaterial 
thing  cannot  suffer  this  fate,  since  it  is  form,  and  form  cannot 
be  separated  from  itself.  Thus,  we  see  that  neither  in  itself 
does  the  soul  carry  any  seeds  of  death  or  corruption,  being 
simple  life  ;  nor  yet  can  it  be  destroyed  by  the  corruption 
of  the  body  on  which  it  never  depends  for  existence. 

But  even  if  it  is  thus  in  itself  intrinsically  incorruptible, 
may  it  not  be  annihilated  by  the  cause  which  gave  it  being  ? 
The  introduction  of  this  question  shows  that  no  finally 
satisfactory  solution  of  our  problem  can  be  arrived  at  without 
acknowledging  the  existence  of  such  a  cause  of  being,  viz. 
God.  Not  only  does  it  seem  that  immortality  without  God 
would  not  be  desirable  ;  but  also,  that  unless  the  soul  is 
dependent  for  its  being  on  a  source  which  is  altogether  per- 
fect and  infinite,  immortality  could  not  be  secure.  The  finite 
cause  and  power  which  brought  it — if  by  an  impossible  sup- 
position it  could  create — into  being  might  fail  to  preserve 
it,  whether  through  malice,  caprice,  or  lack  of  power.  To 
attribute  to  God,  on  the  other  hand,  the  purpose  of  annihi- 
ating  the  souls  He  had  created,  is  an  impossible  supposition. 
Though  it  is  true  He  has  the  power  to  annihilate,  as  to  create; 
nevertheless,  the  exercise  of  this  power  is  excluded  by  His 
essential  perfection  and  wisdom  ;  since  it  is  incredible  that 
all-wise  and  all-knowing  Being  should  deprive  His  creatures 
of  the  nature  which  He  has  given  them.  This  is  precisely  what 
He  would  do  if  He  were  to  annihilate  intellectual  natures, 
since  they  are  essentially  not  subject  to  corruption,  but  have, 


320         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

in  virtue  of  their  nature,  perpetual  being.  Such  a  suggestion 
must  be  particularly  repugnant  to  those  who  are  so  attached 
to  the  inviolability  of  natural  law  that  they  are  unwilling 
to  allow  that  God  can  even  suspend  its  operation.  To 
deprive  a  soul  of  immortality  after  endowing  it  with  an  im- 
mortal nature  would  be  an  inconsistency  even  more  flagrant 
than  would  be  the  endowment  of  material  things  with  a 
nature  which  necessitates  their  coming  together,  in  accord- 
ance with  the  law  of  gravitation,  and  then  preventing  them 
ever  coming  together  in  this  way. 

In  the  Summa  Contra  Gentiles,1  S.  Thomas  gathered 
together  a  great  array  of  arguments  which  all  tend  to  prove 
the  truth  of  personal  immortality  for  man,  and  we  may  con- 
clude this  short  indication  of  some  of  them,  by  reminding 
ourselves  that  what  properly  speaking  perfects  a  man  is 
itself  incorruptible,  viz.  the  knowledge  of  eternal  truths, 
and  the  free  but  undeviating  practice  of  virtue,  which 
certainly  is  not  material.  The  incorruptible  cannot  perfect 
the  corruptible,  or  the  immaterial  what  is  essentially 
material ;  but  a  perfection  must  be  proportionate  to  that 
which  it  perfects,  an  act  to  the  capacity  for  that  act.  We 
cannot,  then,  suppose  that  man  belongs  essentially  to  the 
temporal  order  with  its  change  and  corruption,  but  his  nature 
finds  its  true  perfection  in  a  life  eternal  and  incorruptible, 
where  intellect  and  will  find  their  full  development,  ever 
satisfied  and  never  satiated. 

1  Lib.  II,  cc.  55,  79. 


CHAPTER  XVII 

THE   ORIGIN   OF   LIFE 

The  Origin  of  Life  on  Earth — Opinions — Spontaneous  Generation — 
Two  Forms  of  the  Theory — Their  Possibility. 

Having  now  investigated  the  three  great  divisions  of  animate 
nature,  we  are  in  a  position  to  survey  it  as  a  whole.  We  have 
seen,  in  connection  with  each  of  them,  that  these  three 
species  of  living  things  are  composed  of  individuals  who,  in 
every  case,  act  with  an  intrinsic  tendency  towards  the 
preservation  and  well-being  of  the  living  individual  as  a 
whole,  such  actions  originating  with  the  life-principle 
within  them.  Further,  it  has  been  established  that  through 
the  whole  range  the  individual  living  thing  is  an  essential 
unity,  and  that,  as  between  the  three  grades  of  living  things, 
there  exist  specific  or  essential  differences.  Thus  we  see 
that  the  Aristotelean  definition  of  the  soul  or  life-principle 
which  we  mentioned  at  the  start — the  soul  is  the  first  act  of 
a  physical  organic  body — is  fully  justified. 

If  these  results  as  to  the  world  of  animate  nature  be  taken 
as  established,  we  still  have  left  two  questions  which  relate 
to  it  considered  as  a  whole  :  first,  how  did  life  originate  ? 
and,  secondly,  what  are  the  relations  between  its  different 
manifestations  ? 

The  first  question,  which  is  to  be  discussed  in  this  chapter, 
is  concerned  primarily  with  the  origin  of  life  on  this  planet ; 
and  though,  from  the  point  of  view  of  biological  science,  life, 
if  it  is  allowed  to  be  of  a  different  nature  to  non-living  matter, 
may  have  to  be  accepted  as  an  ultimate  datum,  as  to  the 
origin  of  which  no  significant  question  can  be  asked  ;x  yet, 

1  As  is  asserted  by  Dr.  Johnstone,  The  Philosophy  of  Biology,  pp.  340  f. 
He  says  :  '  The  problem  of  the  origin  of  life,  an  it  is  usually  stated,  is  only 
a  pseudo-problem  ;  we  may  as  usefully  discuss  the  origin  of  the  second 
law  of  thermodynamics  !     If  life  is  not  only  energy  but  also  the  direction 

321 


322         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

from  the  point  of  view  of  philosophy,  this  is  not  so,  since  it 
cannot  be  supposed  that  life,  as  we  observe  it,  is  ultimate  in 
the  order  of  being.  In  the  same  way,  a  physicist  does  not 
enquire  how  natural  laws,  such  as  that  of  entropy,  i.e.  the 
second  law  of  thermodynamics,  came  into  being,  since  these 
laws  (indicating  the  natures  of  things  which  obey  them)  are 
taken  as  ultimate  ;  but  the  same  is  not  true  of  the  philo- 
sopher who  must  try  to  discover  why  nature  is  governed  by 
such  laws,  in  other  words,  to  penetrate  behind  the  laws  to  an 
understanding  of  the  natures  themselves  which  obey  them  ; 
so  that  he  can  properly  ask  what  the  origin  of  these  laws  is. 

If,  then,  we  ask  how  life  originated  on  this  earth,  there  are 
four  possible  answers  :  (i)  that  it  did  not  begin,  but  was 
eternally  present  ;  (2)  that  it  came  to  this  planet  from  some 
other  part  of  the  universe  where  it  was  eternally  present  ; 
(3)  that  it  arose  by  spontaneous  generation  from  inanimate 
matter  ;   (4)  that  it  arose  by  creation. 

As  to  the  first  view,  this  is  clearly  impossible  since  we  know 
that  the  earth  is  itself  not  eternal,  but  had  a  beginning. 
Moreover — and  this  consideration  disposes  of  the  second 
view  also — by  asserting  its  eternity  we  do  not  answer  the 
question  as  to  its  origin,  for  even  if  it  were  supposed  to  be 
eternal  it  would,  since  it  is  not  self-sufficing  and  necessary, 
but  dependent  and  contingent,  still  require  a  source  from 
which  it  eternally  proceeded,  so  that  we  are  no  nearer  to  a 
solution  of  the  problem  of  its  origin. 

The  second  view  encounters,  moreover,  another  insuper- 
able objection,  inasmuch  as  the  assertion  that  it  came  to 
earth  from  some  other  part  of  the  universe  does  not  solve 
the  question  of  its  origin,  but  only  puts  it  one  stage  further 
back.  It  is  interesting,  however,  to  notice  that  this  view 
has  been  held  by  many  eminent  men.  It  seems  to  have  first 
been  put  forward  by  de  Month  vault  in  182 1,  and  was 
developed  thirty  years  later  by  Count  Keyserling,  who  held 
that  life,  like  the  world,  is  eternal,  but  from  time  to  time 

and  co-ordination  of  energies  ;  if  it  is  a  tendency  of  the  same  order,  but 
of  a  different  direction,  from  the  tendency  of  inorganic  processes,  all  that 
biology  can  usefully  do  is  to  inquire  into  the  manner  in  which  this  tendency 
is  manifested  in  material  things  and  energy-transformations.  But  the 
tendency  itself  is  something  elemental.' 


THE   ORIGIN   OF   LIFE  323 

changes  its  habitat.  He  thought  that  it  passes  through  the 
universe  in  the  form  of  living  germs.  Some  thought  these 
germs  were  brought  to  us  in  cosmic  dust  or  comets,  while 
others,  as  Count  de  Salles-Guyon,  Lord  Kelvin,  and  Helm- 
holtz  supposed  them  to  have  come  in  meteorites.  Since, 
however,  the  germs  must  come  not  only  from  the  planets, 
but  from  the  stars,  they  must  be  supposed  to  be  incom- 
bustible, and  even  if  it  were  conceded  that  this  marvellous 
property  might  be  possessed  by  some  very  minute  germs, 
yet  the  minutest  germs  are  destroyed  by  ultra-violet  rays. 
The  theory  is  therefore  unacceptable  from  every  point  of 
view. 1 

Turning  to  the  third  hypothesis,  we  find  that  it  had  a 
longer  and  more  honourable  history.  It  was,  in  fact,  the 
universal  belief  of  men  of  science  till  the  first  part  of  the 
seventeenth  century.  Aristotle  held  that  the  more  imperfect 
animals,  such  as  parasites,  were  spontaneously  generated  by 
warmth,  without  the  intervention  of  any  living  thing.  This 
view  was  also  held  by  S.  Thomas.2 

The  first  doubts  seem  to  have  been  raised  by  Francesco 
Redi  (1626-1697),  who  showed  by  experiment  that  no  living 
organisms  appeared  in  the  flesh  of  a  dead  animal  if  it  were 
carefully  protected  from  the  entry  of  living  germs  from 
without ;  but  he  was  not  so  successful  in  the  case  of  parasites, 
whose  origin  was  not  established  till  the  nineteenth  century. 
The  chief  of  the  experimenters  of  this  time  was  Louis  Pas- 
teur, who  showed  that  all  putrefaction  and  many  kinds  of 
fermentation  are  due  to  the  presence  of  microscopic  living 
organisms  ;  while  Tyndall  showed  that  absolute  sterilisation 
of  infusions  could  be  attained  by  intermittent  applications 
of  heat.  These  discoveries  led  to  the  general  acceptance  of 
the  law  of  biogenesis,  which  does  not,  as  is  sometimes  sup- 
posed, assert  that  every  living  thing  does,  or  still  less  must, 
originate  from  another  living  thing,  but  only  that  there  is  no 
known  instance  of  living  organisms  arising  from  non-living 
matter.     Whether  under  conditions  widely  different  from 

1  Cf.  Perrier,  The  Earth  before  History,  pp.  61  ff. 

1  Cf.  Aristotle,  Met.,  1032a  27 ;  S.  Thomas.  Comm.  in  Met.  (ed.  Cathala), 
1400,  1401  ;  Summa  Theol.,  I,  105,  1,  ad  1  ;  I,  71,  1,  ad  1 ;  I,  72,  ad  5. 


324         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

those  which  come  under  our  observation,  this  could  happen, 
must  necessarily  be,  from  the  scientific  point  of  view,  a 
matter  of  simple  speculation,  since  the  only  scientific 
method  of  deciding  the  question,  that  of  observation  and 
experiment,  is  clearly  not  available.  Consequently,  any 
dogmatic  assertion  that  under  such  conditions  life  did,  in 
fact,  arise  from  non-living  matter  must  be  considered  to  be 
unscientific.1  Many  attempts,  however,  have  been  made  to 
find  some  positive  justification  of  it ;  of  which  the  most 
famous,  or  perhaps  notorious,  is  that  of  Haeckel,  who  pro- 
duced some  of  the  ocean  slime  as  the  primordial  living  sub- 
stance, to  which  Huxley,  who  at  first  accepted  it  as  genuine 
protoplasm,  gave  the  name  of  Bathybius  Haeckeli :  i.e. 
Haeckel's  Low-life.  Huxley  later  identified  it  as  being  only 
a  mineral  precipitate  of  gelatinous  appearance,  which  arises 
when  distilled  alcohol  is  poured  into  sea-water  containing 
organic  matter  in  suspension,  and  so  essentially  a  non-living 
substance.2  Haeckel,  however,  persisted  in  his  defence  of  it ; 
and  an  attempt  has  been  recently  made  to  rehabilitate  it. 
Nevertheless,  it  is  true  to  say  that  the  production  of  the 
living  from  the  non-living,  or  abiogenesis,  as  at  present 
occurring,  finds  no  definite  positive  support  in  modern 
scientific  investigation.  This,  of  course,  leaves  the  question 
of  the  possibility  of  such  an  occurrence  an  open  one  ;  and  a 
decision  with  regard  to  it  can  only  come,  if  at  all,  from  the 
side  of  philosophy.  Now,  with  regard  to  this  possibility, 
two  hypotheses  present  themselves  for  discussion  :  first, 
that  life  was  originally  produced  by  a  fortuitous  combination 
and  disposition  of  inorganic  matter,  or  that  such  matter  was 
combined  and  arranged  and  life  produced  under  the  influence 
of  some  cause  of  another  order  ;  of  what  S.  Thomas  calls  an 
analogous  cause,  which  is  in  itself  superior  to  the  effects 
which  it  produces. 

It  may  be  stated  at  once  that  most  modern  scientists3 
incline  to  accept  the  first  hypothesis  as  a  result  of  their 

1  As,  for  example,  that  of  Perrier  :    '  What  we  are  unable  to  achieve 
was  done  spontaneously  in  the  beginning.'    The  Earth  before  History,  p.  66. 

2  Cf.  Perrier,  op.  cit.,  p.  59. 

3  Cf.  Philosophy  (1932),  art.  by  Prof.  J.  Johnstone,  p.  293.     Cf.  also 
Jeans,  Mysterious  Universe,  pp.  6  ff. 


THE  ORIGIN  OF  LIFE  325 

general  physical  conceptions.  Though  they  admit  that  the 
coming  of  life  by  such  a  chance  combination  of  atoms  is  a 
highly  improbable  event,  in  the  sense  that  the  chances 
against  its  occurrence  are  enormous,  yet  they  do  not  regard 
it  as  inconceivable.1  In  this  belief  they  take  for  granted  that 
life  is  not  essentially  different  from  inorganic  matter  ;  as  is 
shown  by  such  assertions  as  that  it  is  '  just  as  conceivable 
as  would  be  the  "  spontaneous  "  segregation  of,  say,  a  litre 
volume  of  gas  into  two  regions,  one  of  which  had  a  much 
greater  density  than  the  other  one.'2  Evidently,  no  new 
nature  would  appear  in  such  a  segregation,  and  if  '  spon- 
taneous generation  '  is  just  as  conceivable  as  this,  it  will  be 
so  only  if  no  new  nature  appears  in  such  generation,  or  if 
animate  and  inanimate  matter  are  of  the  same  kind.  As, 
then,  we  are  unable  to  accept  this  presupposition,  neither 
can  we  accept  the  conclusion  that  spontaneous  generation, 
due  to  a  chance  combination  of  atoms,  is  conceivable, 
though  improbable.  According  to  the  view  which  we  have 
been  led  by  our  consideration  of  living  things  to  accept, 
these  possess,  in  addition  to  the  properties  of  inanimate  ones, 
various  perfections  which  the  latter  do  not  possess  at  all, 
such  as  the  acts  of  nutrition,  growth,  and  reproduction.  It 
is  here  not  a  question  of  mere  difference  of  properties,  but  of 
a  positive  addition  to  them,  so  that  the  living  thing  possesses 
the  properties  of  non-living  ones,  and  in  addition,  certain 
active  characteristics  which  are  entirely  its  own.  If,  then, 
life  arose  '  spontaneously  '  in  this  sense,  i.e.  by  chance  and 
without  any  additional  principle,  from  purely  inorganic 
matter,  such  positive  activities,  such  increases  of  perfection, 
would  have  to  be  held  to  have  arisen  from  nothing  ;  since 
matter  itself  does  not  possess  them,  and  no  cause  other 
than  brute  matter  is,  in  this  hypothesis,  postulated. 

An  even  more  fundamental  reason  for  disallowing  the 
possibility  of  life  originating  solely  from  a  random  combina- 
tion of  inert  bodies  is  to  be  found  in  a  consideration  of  the 
finality  of  living  things.  These  are  essentially  one,  having 
one  form  only,  which  form  tends  to  a  single  end,  the  good  of 
the  individual  as  a  whole,  and  of  the  species.     That  the 

1  Cf.  Johnstone,  art.  cit.  2  Ibid.,  loc.  cit. 


326         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

multiple  tendencies,  then,  of  a  number  of  inanimate  bodies 
should  produce  this  single  unified  tendency  of  the  living 
thing,  in  the  absence  of  any  directive  power  to  unify  and 
co-ordinate  them,  is  strictly  speaking  inconceivable.  The 
unconditioned  union  of  things  which  are  essentially  different 
is  impossible,  for  being  by  nature  many  they  cannot  also  be 
by  nature  one,  unless  they  are  brought  into  this  unity  by 
some  unifying  and  directive  principle.  Such  a  principle 
would  not  be  present  in  the  hypothesis  we  are  considering, 
since  it  allows  of  no  principle  but  the  unco-ordinated  and 
divergent  forces  of  inanimate  elements.  This  doctrine  as  to 
the  impossibility  of  the  unconditional  union  of  the  many  is 
common  to  Platonism  and  Aristoteleanism,  and,  indeed,  to 
the  whole  tradition  of  the  '  philosophia  perennis.'  We  shall 
have  occasion  to  consider  it  again  at  a  later  stage. 

It  will  be  seen  that  the  reasons  we  have  just  advanced  do 
not  militate  against  the  possibility  of  life  having  arisen  from 
inanimate  matter  under  the  direction  and  influence  of  some 
power  higher  than  that  of  matter  itself,  by  whose  means  life 
is  brought  from  a  state  of  potentiality  to  one  of  actuality. 
It  was  in  this  way  that  S.  Thomas  conceived  of  some  forms 
of  life  being  spontaneously  generated  from  inanimate  matter 
under  the  directive  and  unifying  action  of  God  ;  and  the 
same  conception  may  perhaps  be  found  in  the  theory  of 
Emergent  Evolution,  which  has  had  a  certain  vogue  in 
recent  times.  Its  exponents,  however,  do  not  seem  to  speak 
with  any  great  consistency.1 

As  to  the  probability  of  such  emergence  of  life  being  a 
fact,  the  evidence  at  present  appears  to  be  inadequate  for 
the  formation  of  any  definite  conclusion,  but  it  does  not 
seem  that  a  Thomist  is  obliged  to  bang,  bolt,  and  bar  the 
door  on  its  possibility.2  If  it  is  not  thought  probable  we 
shall,  of  course,  adopt  the  only  remaining  hypothesis  to 
explain  the  origin  of  life,  viz.  that  it  was  in  the  first  instance 
created  by  God.    Even  if  this  be  so,  we  may  still  be  in  doubt 

1  Cf.  McDougall,  Modem  Materialism  and  Emergent  Evolution,  pp.  152 
ff.  ;  Lloyd  Morgan,  Emergent  Evolution  ;  Lloyd  Morgan,  Essay  on  Biology, 
pp.  in  ff.  in  Evolution  in  the  Light  of  Modern  Knowledge. 

*•  With  regard  to  its  probability  cf.  McDougall,  op.  cit.,  Ch.  V.  Its 
possibility  is  discussed  in  Revue  Thomiste,  1923,  pp.  298  ff.,  305  ff. 


THE  ORIGIN  OF  LIFE  327 

as  to  the  origin  of  the  different  species  of  living  things.  Are 
we  to  attribute  their  existence  to  a  series  of  creative  acts,  or  is 
there  reason  to  think  that  they  have  been  developed,  and 
progressively  differentiated  from  one  another,  by  a  purely 
natural  process  ;  so  that  all  of  them  are  to  be  thought  of  as 
being  descended  from  some  one  primitive  form  of  life  ? 

This  is  the  question  of  evolution  or  transformism,  the  dis- 
cussion of  which  in  the  next  chapter  will  conclude  our  survey 
of  the  world  of  animate  nature. 


CHAPTER  XVIII 

TRANSFORMISM 

Preliminary  Remarks — Sketch  of  Evolutionary  Theories — Lamarck — 
Darwin — The  Materialist  Theory — Reasons  which  Exclude  It — 
Consideration  of  Evolutionary  Theories  in  General. 

Probably  no  scientific  theory  has  aroused  such  widespread 
and  heated  controversy  as  that  which  is  popularly  known  as 
the  theory  of  evolution.  This  was  due,  not  to  its  scientific 
content,  but  to  its  philosophical  and  religious  bearings,  since 
it  seemed  to  imply  an  entire  absence  of  purpose  in  nature  ; 
and,  what  appeared  more  objectionable  both  to  the  man  in 
the  street  and  the  upholders  of  orthodox  religion,  that  man 
was  merely  an  intelligent  kind  of  ape.  This  suggestion  was 
not  merely  unflattering,  but  seemed  to  be  clearly  contrary 
to  the  account  of  man's  origin  given  in  the  Bible,  on  both  of 
which  accounts  it  was  at  first  vigorously  repudiated. 

The  controversy  has  now  died  down  to  a  great  extent, 
largely  because  prolonged  investigation  has  shown  what  are 
the  true  implications  of  the  theory,  as  well  as  bringing  to 
light  the  serious,  and  perhaps  insurmountable,  difficulties 
which  attach  to  the  suggested  explanations  of  the  method 
by  which  evolution  has  proceeded.  Theological  opposition, 
in  England  at  any  rate,  has  practically  ceased,  owing  to  the 
abandonment  by  the  Protestant  churches  of  belief  in  the 
Biblical  account  of  creation,  and  their  acceptance  in  its 
place  of  the  infallible  decisions  of  the  biologists.  It  is  curious 
to  notice  that  both  sides  appeal  to  authority  for  the  settle- 
ment of  this  question.  In  its  early  stages  the  theologians 
attempted  to  silence  the  Darwinians  by  the  authority  of 
Genesis,  while  at  present  the  evolutionists  try  to  silence  the 
doubter  by  the  authority  of  scientific  opinion.  This  fact 
suggests  the  reflection  that  the  truth  or  falsity  of  this  theory 
may  not  indeed  be  very  plain  to  reason,  if  our  guides  urge  us 

328 


TRANSFORMISM  329 

to  accept  or  reject  it  on  faith.  These  attempts  at  bullying 
failed,  as  they  were  bound  to  do,  since  those  who  were 
bludgeoned  with  the  Bible  were  at  least  doubtful  as  to  its 
infallibility,  and  those  who  are  now  threatened  with  '  scien- 
tific opinion  '  and  the  views  of  '  every  educated  man  '  are 
equally  doubtful  as  to  the  infallibility  of  science.  The 
method  of  authoritative  imposition  of  beliefs,  though 
invaluable  if  the  competence  of  the  authority  be  admitted, 
is,  consequently,  not  one  of  universal  application,  being 
limited  to  the  circle  of  '  true  believers.'  If  we  are,  then,  as 
philosophic  method  demands,  to  consider  this  question 
solely  by  the  aid  of  natural  reason,  no  fulminations  of 
scientists  accusing  us  of  heresy,  or  of  ignorance  and  stupidity, 
if  we  find  ourselves  unconvinced  of  the  truth  of  their  dogmas, 
can  carry  any  weight  with  us  ;  unless  on  other  grounds  we 
have  already  admitted  the  infallibility  of  scientific  opinion. 
In  its  proper  sphere,  and  when  it  can  be  had,  authoritative 
decision  is  an  invaluable  method  of  settling  troublesome 
questions  ;  but  this  sphere  is  that  of  faith,  not  of  reason.  As 
S.  Thomas  says  :  '  Locus  ab  auctoritate  quce  fundatur  super 
ratione  humana  est  infirmissimus.'1 

We  can  therefore  approach  this  question  with  an  open 
mind,  and  see  what  reason  can  tell  us  as  to  the  possibility  of 
transformism.  If  it  is  found  to  be  possible,  the  question  of 
its  probability  is  one  which  must  be  decided  in  the  light  of 
available  evidence,  a  discussion  of  which  belongs  rather  to 
natural  science  than  to  philosophy. 

There  is  probably  no  one  who  has  not  at  least  a  vague 
idea  of  what  the  word  evolution,  as  applied  to  living  things, 
means  ;  but  in  ordinary  language  it  is  confined  to  one  par- 
ticular transformation  of  a  species,  that  which  is  naturally  of 
most  interest  to  ourselves,  the  transformation  of  some  ape- 
like creature  into  man.  This  popular  use  of  the  word  is, 
however,  far  from  expressing  the  scientific  idea  ;  and  though 
fortunately  we  are  not  obliged  to  consider  all  its  scientific 
applications,  we  must  get  some  more  precise  notion  of  it 
than  this  narrow  and  inexact  one. 

The  word  '  evolution  '  is  itself  not  a  strikingly  happy  one, 

1  Summa  Theol.,  I,  Q.  I,  a.  8,  ad  2. 


330         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSPOHY 

as  applied  to  the  transformation  of  living  species,  since  many 
things  unroll  without  being  transformed,  as  carpets  and 
snakes,  while  the  transformation  which  is  asserted  in  most 
modern  evolutionary  theories  can  hardly  be  called  an  unroll- 
ing. It  has,  however,  been  commonly  adopted  in  England, 
and  applied  not  only  to  the  realm  of  living  things,  as  in 
Biology  and  Psychology,  but  also  to  the  development  of  the 
material  universe  in  Cosmogony,  and  to  its  minutest  con- 
stituents in  Physics  and  Chemistry.  Whether  it  is,  in  fact, 
applicable  to  any  of  these  spheres  except  Biology,  in  a  sense 
which  is  properly  speaking  analogical  to  that  which  it  con- 
veys in  this  science,  is  very  doubtful,  and  has  possibly  led  to 
confusion  of  ideas  ;  but  this  is  a  question  which  lies  outside 
the  boundaries  of  our  present  discussion. 

The  term  Transformism,  which  is  in  general  use  on  the 
continent  of  Europe,  is  much  more  exact,  and  indicates  the 
transformation  of  living  things  into  new  species. 

The  idea  of  such  transformism,  or  gradual  development  of 
living  things  from  pre-existing  forms,  is  not  a  modern  one, 
but  at  least  as  old  as  the  fifth  century  B.C.  It  occurred  to 
the  earliest  Greek  thinkers,  and  even  the  Darwinian  method 
of  evolution  by  survival  of  the  fittest  was  suggested  by 
Empedocles  (495-435  B.C.).  Aristotle,  who  was,  of  course, 
eminent  among  the  Greeks  for  his  biological  observations, 
made  the  idea  more  precise  ;  but  his  theory  of  transformism 
consistently  with  his  general  fundamental  principles  was,  in 
contrast  with  those  of  his  predecessors,  a  decidedly  teleologi- 
cal  one.  Rejecting  the  idea  of  the  survival  of  the  fittest,  he 
maintains  that  nature  successively  adapts  organs  to  their 
function,  and  this  in  the  order  of  their  necessity,  those 
essential  to  life  coming  first,  to  be  followed  by  those  which 
are  of  service  in  the  full  functioning  of  the  nature  of  parti- 
cular species.  Thus  those  animals  which  have  eyes  have 
them  in  order  that  they  may  exercise  the  powers  of  their 
nature.  What  determines  the  evolution  of  the  animal  is 
their  nature,  which  strives  to  produce  a  certain  result,  so 
that  '  the  process  of  evolution  is  for  the  sake  of  the  nature 
evolved,  and  not  this  nature  for  the  sake  of  the  process.'1 

1  Cf.  Aristotle,  De  partibus  animalium,  640s  18. 


TRANSFORMISM  331 

S.  Augustine  is  generally  thought  to  have  been  favourable 
to  a  view  of  evolution  in  some  form,  and  in  spite  of  doubts 
raised  as  to  the  precise  meaning  of  his  theory,  it  can  hardly  be 
denied  that  he  entertained  the  idea  of  new  species  arising 
in  virtue  of  the  powers  bestowed  on  matter  at  the  creation. 

It  is  not  easy  to  determine  S.  Thomas'  precise  view  on 
this  question,  but  he  did  not  allow  that  material  elements 
have  in  themselves,  or  essentially,  the  power  of  producing 
all  animals,  though  they  could  do  so  under  the  influence  of 
an  analogous  cause.1 

Though  Cajetan  supported  a  form  of  evolutionary  theory, 
in  later  times,  and  under  the  influence  of  Suarez,  it  was 
generally  abandoned  among  theologians,  and  the  doctrine 
of  special  creation  was  left  without  a  rival.  According  to 
this  view,  all  existing  species  had  been  created  at  the  begin- 
ning in  their  present  forms  ;  so  that  as  Linnaeus  says  :  '  tot 
nunc  species  sunt,  quot  ab  initio  creavit  infinitum  ens.'  In 
order  to  square  this  view  with  the  apparent  appearance  of 
new  species,  some  had  recourse  to  a  series  of  special  creations, 
thus  dropping  the  '  ab  initio '  ;  or  else  maintained  that  the 
so-called  new  species  were  not  properly  species  at  all,  but 
merely  racial  variations  of  already  existing  species.  It  was  not 
until  the  nineteenth  century  that  evolutionary  theories  again 
became  prominent,  and  eventually  were  generally  accepted. 

The  modem  history  of  the  problem  really  begins  with 
Lamarck,  the  most  important  forerunner  of  Darwin,  whose 
theory  of  evolution  was  first  outlined  in  1802,  and  fully 
developed  in  his  Philosophic  Zoologique  in  1809. 

Four  laws  constitute  the  skeleton,  so  to  speak,  of  his 
system.  These  are  :  (1)  the  law  of  growth,  (2)  of  functional 
reaction,  (3)  of  use  and  disuse,  and  (4)  of  use — inheritance. 

The  first  asserts  that  the  size  of  the  living  being  is  increased 
by  the  activities  of  this  body  itself  up  to  some  limit  imposed 
by  its  own  nature  ;  the  second  that  new  organs  arise  in 
response  to  some  new  felt  need  ;  the  third  that  organs 
develop  proportionately  to  their  use,  and  atrophy  in  so  far  as 

1  Cf.  Summa  Theol.,  I,  Q.  71  ;  1.69,2  ;  1.73,  a.i,  ad  3.  The  opinions  of 
S.  Augustine  and  S.  Thomas  have  recently  been  discussed  by  Dr.  Messenger 
in  his  Evolution  and  Theology,  Part  I,  Chaps.  VIII-X,  and  Ch.  XIII. 


332         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

they  are  not  used  ;  while  the  fourth  maintains  that  charac- 
teristics acquired  by  an  individual  organism  in  the  course  of 
its  life  are  transmitted  to  this  individual's  descendents. 

The  last  two  laws  are  particularly  interesting,  since  the 
third  asserts  that  bodily  structure  depends  on  function,  and 
the  last  the  heritability  of  acquired  characters,  a  doctrine 
which  is  still  the  subject  of  acute  controversy.  All  four  laws, 
it  should  be  noticed,  embody  a  teleological  conception  of 
evolution,  and  so,  to  this  extent,  are  in  line  with  the  Aris- 
totelean  ideas  on  this  subject. 

In  the  period  immediately  preceding  the  publication  of 
Darwin's  work  the  transmutation  theory  was  shelved  or 
rejected,  so  that  the  appearance  of  The  Origin  of  Species  in 
1859,  followed  by  that  of  The  Descent  of  Man  in  1871,  had  a 
startling  and  sensational  effect.  The  reason  of  this  was  not 
merely,  and  not  chiefly,  that  transformism  had  fallen  into 
disrepute,  so  that  Darwin's  ideas  had  a  certain  freshness  and 
novelty,  but  essentially  to  the  fact  that  he  was  the  first  to 
give  it  such  a  basis  as  seemed  to  establish  it  firmly  as  a  fact. 
It  was  not  his  theory,  but  his  facts  which  revolutionised 
scientific  opinion.  The  vast  accumulation  of  facts  which  his 
laborious  researches,  in  the  five  years  in  which  he  was 
travelling  in  the  Beagle,  and  the  twenty  succeeding  years, 
had  enabled  him  to  collect,  made  a  profound  impression  on 
biologists  ;  and  the  sensation  caused  among  the  general 
public  by  his  theory,  and  especially  by  his  account  of  man's 
origin,  is  largely  attributable  to  its  antiteleological,  and 
apparently  anti-religious,  tendency,  due  to  his  attributing 
transformism  to  Natural  Selection,  which  works  blindly  and 
automatically.  Prof.  Hobson  asserts  that  '  after  Darwin's 
work  it  (i.e.  the  fact  of  organic  evolution)  was  no  longer  a 
speculative  hypothesis,  but  a  well-attested  deduction  from 
observation.  As  regards  the  position  of  Natural  Selection 
as  the  chief  factor  in  Evolution,  it  is  not  possible  to  speak  so 
positively :  on  this  matter  the  opinions  of  Biologists  have 
been,  and  still  are,  much  divided.'1  This  statement  probably 
represents  the  state  of  scientific  opinion  at  the  present  day 
fairly  accurately. 

1  E.  W.  Hobson,  The  Domain  of  Natural  Science,  pp.  437  fif. 


TRANSFORMISM  333 

From  what  has  been  said  the  reader  will  have  gathered 
that  there  are  three  main  elements  in  Darwin's  theory.  The 
first  the  establishment  by  observation  of  the  fact  that  new 
species  have  originated  from  older  ones,  the  new  being 
descended  from  some  of  the  individuals  of  the  older  species. 
The  second  element  is  the  attributing  of  this  emergence  of 
new  species  primarily  and  principally  to  Natural  Selection, 
which  works  by  causing  those  individuals,  which  happen  to 
vary  slightly  from  the  norm  of  their  species,  to  be  more,  or 
less,  capable  of  surviving  than  normal  members  of  the 
species  would  be,  according  as  the  possession  of  such  vari- 
ations puts  them  in  an  advantageous  or  disadvantageous 
position  in  the  struggle  for  life.  So,  for  example,  we  might 
suppose  that  those  giraffes  which  have  the  longest  necks 
would  more  easily  be  able  to  reach  the  higher  branches  of 
trees,  and  so  could  procure  food  more  easily  than  the  shorter- 
necked  ones  ;  and  thus,  if  food  was  scarce,  only  the  long- 
necked  ones  would  survive,  the  others  dying  of  starvation. 
The  same  sort  of  process  would  occur  in  animals  which 
possessed  superior  weapons  of  defence  or  offence.  Thus 
nature  herself  would  gradually  eliminate  the  less  fit,  but 
blindly,  and  without  any  purpose.  This  brings  us  to  the 
last  element  of  the  theory,  which  is  perhaps  the  most 
important  from  the  philosophical  point  of  view^  viz.  its  anti- 
teleological  tendency  ;  since  it  accounts  for  what  appears  to 
be  a  purposive  adaptation  of  the  various  species  to  their 
environment  by  a  process  which  eliminates  purpose  altogether. 
Thus  the  peculiarities  which  appear  to  have  been  designed 
in  order  that  the  individual  may  survive  owe  their  origin  to 
chance,  and  their  continuance  to  the  less  easy  elimination  of 
the  individuals  possessing  them  ;  and  not  to  any  striving 
on  the  part  of  the  individual  itself.  Since  they  have  come 
about  by  chance  they  cannot  be  purposive,  either  in  their 
inception  or  their  continuance.  As  Huxley  says  :  '  Darwin 
gave  the  death  blow  to  teleology  by  showing  that  apparently 
purposive  structures  could  arise  by  means  of  a  non-purposive 
mechanism.' 

In  this  way  it  was  thought  that  Biology  was  brought  into 
line  with  Physics,  from  which  purpose  had  already  been 


334         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

excluded.  As  Tennyson  says  in  In  Memoriam,  alluding  to 
the  mechanistic  view  of  Physics  : 

'  The  stars  '  she  whispers  '  blindly  run  '  ; 

and  now  it  appeared  that  living  things,  animals  and  man 
also  '  blindly  run,'  driven  on  by  the  whips  of  uncontrollable 
forces  to  an  inexorable  doom. 

It  has  been  necessary  to  give  this  account  of  the  theories 
of  Lamarck  and  Darwin  in  order  to  bring  into  prominence 
those  characteristics  of  modern  evolutionary  theories  which 
are  of  importance  from  a  philosophical  point  of  view.  But 
it  would  not  be  to  our  purpose,  even  if  it  were  possible,  to 
trace  the  history  of  these  theories  to  the  present  day  ;  since 
the  modern  theories,  though  showing  many  marked  variations 
from  those  of  Darwin  and  Lamarck,  from  which  they  are 
descended,  have  yet  not  changed  their  species,  but  remain 
true  to  the  general  principles  which  governed  the  parent 
theories.  Thus  interest  has  chiefly  centred  since  Darwin's 
time  on  the  discussion  as  to  the  relative  importance  of 
Natural  Selection  and  the  inheritance  of  acquired  characters 
as  the  causes  of  mutations,  the  first  being  stressed  by  the 
neo-Darwinians,  and  the  second  by  the  neo-Lamarckians ; 
and,  speaking  generally,  we  have  two  theories  or  groups  of 
theories,  one  of  the  Lamarckian  and  teleological,  the  other 
of  the  Darwinian  or  antiteleological  type.  The  most 
important  modification  introduced  into  evolutionary  theories 
of  recent  years  is  the  assigning  of  the  transformation  of 
species  by  some  scientists  rather  to  sudden  large  mutations 
than  to  the  slow  accumulation  of  small  ones,  as  was  postu- 
lated by  Darwin's  original  theory.1  This  modification  was 
due  to  the  investigations  and  discoveries  of  Mendel,  de  Vries, 
Batesori,  and  others,  which  threw  doubt  on  the  truth  of  the 
hypothesis  that  transformation  of  species  was  produced  by 
an  accumulation  of  small  variations.  This  doubt  was 
increased  by  the  researches  of  Johannsen,  Agar,  and  Jennings, 
which  seemed  to  show  that  the  small  variations  postulated 
by  the  Darwinian  theory  were  not  inheritable ;  and  thus 

1  Cf.  E.  W.  Hobson,  The  Domain  of  Natural  Science,  pp.  449  £f.  ; 
Dampier-Whetham,  A  History  of  Science,  pp.  247  ff. 


TRANSFORMISM  335 

there  arose  a  tendency  altogether  to  discredit  Natural 
Selection,  as  the  instrument  of  evolution.1 

Thus,  while  some  biologists  continue  to  maintain  the 
sufficiency  of  Natural  Selection  as  an  explanation  of  trans- 
formism,  many  others  incline  to  regard  use  and  disuse  and 
purposive  striving  as  its  chief  causes,  while  others  again  are 
not  prepared  to  commit  themselves  to  any  opinion  as  to  its 
cause.  So  Bateson  said  :  '  In  dim  outline  evolution  is 
evident  enough.  From  the  facts  it  is  a  conclusion  which 
inevitably  follows.  But  that  particular  and  essential  bit  of 
the  theory  of  evolution  which  is  concerned  with  the  origin 
and  nature  of  species  remains  utterly  mysterious.'2 

From  all  this  one  thing  is  very  plain,  viz.  that  there  is  not 
that  unanimity  with  regard  to  the  theory  of  evolution  which 
is  often  asserted,  so  that  a  controversialist  who  demands  its 
acceptance  because  it  is  the  opinion  of  all  educated  men  is 
not  only  irrational,  as  we  have  seen,  but  also  disingenuous. 
In  fact,  it  is  only  the  materialists  or  '  rationalists  '  who 
adopt  this  unreasonable  method  of  forcing  their  opinions 
down  the  throats  of  others  ;  and  it  will  be  convenient  to 
examine  this  extreme  form  of  evolutionism  before  passing 
on  to  see  what  light,  if  any,  Thomistic  principles  can  throw 
on  the  theory  of  transformism  in  general. 

The  professed  Materialists,  then,  recognising  no  other 
reality  than  matter,  assert  that  all  species  of  living  things 
have  arisen  from  inorganic  matter ;  the  first  forms  of  life 
coming  about  by  spontaneous  generation,  and  later  ones 
being  differentiated  from  the  primitive  forms  by  a  process  of 
blind  determined  law ;  without  any  internal  teleological 
tendency,  or  any  intervention  of  the  first  cause,  which  by 
hypothesis  does  not  exist.  The  chief  advantage  of  this 
theory,  from  the  philosophical  point  of  view,  is  that  it  gives 
a  complete  unity  to  all  our  knowledge  of  the  world,  every- 
thing being  wholly  and  essentially  material,  though  if 
thought  and  knowledge  be,  as  the  theory  demands,  but 
secretions  of  the  brain,  the  advantage  is  more  apparent  than 

1  Cf.  Evolution  in  the  Light  of  Modern  Knowledge,  pp.  224  ff. 

2  William  Bateson,  Naturalist.  Memoir  by  Beatrice  Bateson,  p.  395, 
quoted  by  Dampier-Whetham,  op.  cit.,  p.  353. 


336         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

real.  For  this  reason  and  because  the  theory,  when  thus 
plainly  stated,  seems  self-condemned,  we  find  that  its 
adherents  are  not  very  anxious  to  set  it  down  in  black  and 
white,  but  are  inclined  to  hedge  and  to  amuse  themselves  by 
ridiculing  the  '  Fundamentalists  ' ;  instead  of  establishing 
their  own  position.  We  should  observe,  however,  that  the 
slightest  departure  from  this  materialist  scheme  breaks  the 
unity  of  the  conception,  and  readmits  those  realities  which 
the  materialists  are  bent  on  excluding,  viz.  immaterial  or 
spiritual  ones. 

The  theory  was  put  forward  in  an  uncompromising  form 
by  Haeckel  in  the  last  century ;  and  is  adhered  to,  at  the 
present  day,  by  Biological  Materialists,  such  as  Sir  Arthur 
Keith,  and  J.  B.  S.  Haldane  ;  while  Bertrand  Russell  has,  as 
it  seems  very  reluctantly,  made  an  act  of  infra-natural  faith 
in  the  same  view. 

Since,  from  their  own  point  of  view,  the  opinions  of  such 
people  are  merely  physical  states  induced  by  their  own  bodily 
conditions,  no  doubt  they  would  be  content  to  be  dealt  with 
rather  by  medical  than  philosophic  methods.  Nevertheless, 
as  we  do  not  concede  their  premises,  it  is  worth  while  to  see, 
for  our  own  satisfaction,  whether  such  an  attitude  as  theirs 
is  compatible  with  reason. 

It  is,  of  course,  obvious  that  since  this  theory  denies  that 
there  is  any  purpose,  or  teleology,  in  the  evolutionary  process, 
it  denies  also  the  principle  of  finality,  according  to  which 
every  agent  acts  for  an  end.  Can  this  denial  be  rationally 
sustained  ?  We  can  see  the  answer  to  this  question  by  con- 
sidering the  consequences  which  follow  from  the  denial  of 
finality. 

First  of  all,  it  is  clear  that  any  agent,  when  in  act,  is  acting 
in  a  fixed  way  :  it  is  performing  this  act  and  no  other.  Its 
act,  therefore,  has  a  definite  direction  and  achieves  a  definite 
result.  All  this  is  allowed  by  the  materialists  who  maintain, 
in  fact,  that  biologically  useful  characters  achieve  by  their 
use  the  survival  of  their  owner.  If  they  do  this,  they  do  it 
because  they  are  a  certain  definite  kind  of  character,  e.g.  a 
longer  as  compared  with  a  shorter  neck  in  a  giraffe.  Now, 
it  is  asserted  that  though  the  particular  actions  by  whose 


TRANSFORMISM  337 

means  the  process  is  carried  on  have  a  definite  direction  and 
tendency,  yet  the  process  as  a  whole  has  no  purpose.  It  is 
clear,  however,  that  the  evolutionary  process  is  not  some- 
thing distinct  from  the  actions  of  the  evolving  things,  but  is 
merely  the  resultant  of  all  these  actions,  and  it  is  impossible 
to  see  how  if  all  its  components  have  one  definite  tendency 
the  process  itself  should  have  none.  But,  it  will  be  said,  the 
Materialists  do  not  maintain  that  it  has  no  tendency,  and,  in 
fact,  affirm  that  it  causes  the  fittest  to  survive  ;  what  they 
do  maintain  is  that  it  has  no  purpose,  no  conscious  tendency, 
no  plan.  Let  us  then  consider  what  it  is  that  makes  an 
inanimate  thing  act  in  a  determined  way  and  consequently, 
without  knowing  it,  tend  to  a  definite  end.  Surely  it  is 
because  it  has  a  definite  and  determined  nature  :  just  as  the 
eye  sees  and  does  not  hear  or  smell,  because  of  its  particular 
structure.  It  is  easy  to  see,  then,  that  any  being  which  has  a 
determinate  nature  must  act  in  a  determinate  way,  such 
direction  of  its  action  being  due  to  the  fact  that  its  nature  is 
of  a  particular  kind.  Now,  this  theory  of  evolution  has  as  its 
object  the  explanation  of  the  way  in  which  all  things  come 
by  their  determinate  nature,  and  it  cannot,  therefore,  assume 
a  determinate  nature  as  a  starting  point.  It  must,  therefore, 
start  with  an  indeterminate  being,  a  thing  with  no  definite 
nature  at  all ;  a  thing,  then,  which  is  either  simply  nothing, 
or  at  best  a'  pure  capacity  or  potentiality  for  everything.  If 
it  is  nothing  we  are  left  with  the  assertion  that  from  nothing 
everything  comes ;  which  is  simply  unintelligible,  and 
obviously  not  an  explanation.  If  it  is  a  pure  capacity  for 
everything,  having  no  determination  of  its  own,  from  what 
does  it  derive  the  determination  which  starts  the  evolutionary 
process  ?  Evidently  not  from  itself  ;  and  consequently  from 
something  else,  which  has  a  determinate  nature  and  action 
of  its  own,  i.e.  from  something  which  determines  itself,  and 
so  acts  with  purpose  and  intention.  Such  a  being  as  this  is, 
however,  absolutely  excluded  by  the  materialist  hypothesis, 
inasmuch  as  it  denies  finality  of  purpose  altogether,  and 
moreover  is,  as  we  saw,  obliged  to  start  with  the  altogether 
indeterminate.  By  denying  finality,  then,  it  is  driven  to 
hold  that  the  first  being  is  not  even  a  pure  capacity  for  all 


338         MODERN  THOMISTIC  PHILOSOPHY 

things,  but  strictly  nothing ;  and  is  essentially  irrational 
and  unintelligible. 

The  Scholastics,  by  means  of  their  highly  polished  tech- 
nical language,  can  express  this  argument  very  clearly  and 
concisely.  So  they  say  that  every  agent  must  act  for  an 
end,  at  least  in  the  order  of  execution,  for  otherwise  it  would 
not  do  one  thing  rather  than  another.  This  intention  of  the 
agent  to  gain  a  certain  end,  may  be  conscious,  as  in  man,  or 
unconscious,  as  in  inanimate  bodies.  But  even  if  unconscious 
it  is  still  purposive  since  otherwise  its  tendency  in  a  definite 
direction  would  be  without  reason  of  being.  For  this  deter- 
minate direction  must  be  in  the  agent,  and  if  it  is  not  present 
in  it  by  conscious  purpose,  so  that  the  agent  actively  directs 
itself  to  the  end,  it  must  be  passively  directed  to  it.  Such 
passive  direction,  however,  presupposes  active  direction 
which  imparts  it,  and  in  the  last  resort,  active  self-determin- 
ing, or  conscious,  direction.  So  there  is  conscious  or  uncon- 
scious purpose  in  the  action  of  every  agent,  and  the  maxim  : 
'  potentia  dicitur  ad  actum  '  is  universally  true.  The  whole 
raison  d'etre  of  any  capacity,  and  so  of  any  agent,  is  in  its 
power  of  producing  the  effect,  and  so  in  its  tendency  towards 
that  effect,  that  act  or  perfection.1 

To  deny  such  finality,  therefore,  as  the  materialist  evolu- 
tionists do,  is  to  deny  the  reason  of  being  of  the  determinate 
direction  of  the  agents,  or  to  assert  that  something  is  which 
has  no  reason  to  be.  This  is  obviously  not  to  explain  it ; 
and  is,  moreover,  an  assertion  that  something  can  and  does 
come  from  nothing.2 

The  same  conclusion  is  arrived  at  if  we  look  at  this  process 
from  the  point  of  view  of  efficient  causality,  for  few  would 
be  found  to  deny  that  life  is  a  positive  addition  to  matter 
without  life,  sentience  to  matter  which  is  living  but  not 
sentient,  intelligence  or  reason  to  being  which  is  devoid  of 
these.  Now,  according  to  this  theory,  matter  destitute  of 
life,  of  its  own  power  produces  it,  living  matter  destitute  of 
sentience,  brings  it  forth,  and  sentient  life  having  no  intel- 

1  Cf.  S.  Thomas,  Summa  Theol.,  IaIIaeF  Q.  i,  a.  2. 

2  Cf.  Garigou-Lagrange,  De  Revelatione,  Vol.  I,  pp.  255  ff.,  259  f.,  and 
the  same  author's  La  Realisme  du  Principe  de  Finalite,  Ch.  II. 


TRANSFORMISM  339 

lect,  evolves  this  from  itself.  In  each  case  the  greater  being 
produced  by  the  less,  something  is  caused  by  nothing. 

Further,  no  reason  can  be  assigned  in  this  theory  why 
evolution,  the  first  modification,  and  the  perfection  of  the 
evolutionary  process  should  be  at  all  rather  than  not  be  ; 
while  at  the  same  time  it  is  asserted  that  they  are.  Thus 
evolution  can  have  no  reason  of  being  either  in  something 
other  than  itself,  there  being  no  cause  apart  from  it,  nor  yet 
in  itself,  for  it  is  a  movement  or  transit  from  indetermination 
to  determination,  from  potency  to  act,  which  cannot  come 
about  of  itself,  since  indetermination  neither  is,  nor  contains 
in  itself,  determination.  It  has,  and  can  have,  therefore, 
no  reason  of  being  according  to  this  view. 

As  Professor  A.  E.  Taylor  points  out,  evolution,  if  it  is  to 
be  thinkable  at  all,  must  presuppose  both  environment  and 
the  environed  interacting  on  one  another  :  '  When  there  is 
change,  there  is  reason  for  change  .  .  .  and  the  reason  for  a 
change  can  only  be  found  in  something  not  involved  in  that 
change.  It  follows  that  if  there  is  such  a  thing  as  a  process 
of  change  with  a  definite  and  discoverable  law  which  embraces 
the  whole  of  physical  reality,  the  whole  of  physical  reality 
must  have  a  non-physical  environment.'1 

Now,  it  is  precisely  this  environment  which  is  denied  in 
the  theory  we  are  considering,  which  is  thus  strictly  speaking 
unthinkable. 

We  are  forced  to  the  same  conclusion  when  we  consider 
the  first  modification  which  inaugurates  the  evolutionary 
process.  It  is  ascribed  in  the  theory  to  chance  ;  and  this 
phrase  might  mean  either  that  chance  is  the  cause  and 
reason  of  its  appearance,  or  that  we  do  not  know  what  factor 
in  nature  actually  was  responsible  for  it.  No  doubt,  it  is  the 
second  sense  which  is  intended,  since  chance  cannot  be  con- 
ceived as  a  thing  or  reason  which  could  of  itself  produce  a 
positive  effect.  But  the  second  sense  does  not  avoid  the 
difficulty,  since  the  unknown  element  in  the  situation, 
whether  internal  to  the  being  which  produces  the  modifica- 
tion, or  external  to  it,  would  in  its  turn  have  to  be  accounted 

1  A.  E.  Taylor,  Evolution  in  the  Light  of  Modern  Knowledge,  Ch.  XII, 
pp.  449  ff.  Cf.  Lossky,  art.  '  The  Limits  of  Evolution  '  in  the  Journal  of 
Philosophical  Studies,  October  1927. 

Z 


340  MODERN   THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

for.  Here  a^ain,  it  cannot  be  accounted  for  by  '  chance,' 
using  chance  in  the  first  of  the  senses  given  above,  and  so 
once  more  this  must  be  accounted  for  by  a  further  unknown 
factor  in  the  physical  situation.  Now  we  cannot  go  on  for 
ever  finding  the  reason  of  one  unknown  factor  in  a  preceding 
one,  not  because  we  should  get  tired  of  so  doing,  as  has  been 
suggested,  but  because  each  unknown  factor  essentially 
depends  on  another,  so  that  all  of  them  must  in  the  last  resort 
depend  either  on  some  determinate  and  knowable  character 
in  the  physical  situation  and  not  on  chance,  or  else  depend 
on  something  outside  the  series  altogether.  For  if  the 
material  world,  which  in  the  end  produces  the  modified 
being,  had  no  determinate  nature  at  all  it  would  be  useless 
to  look  upon  it  as  the  source  of  the  determinate  modihcation  ; 
and  if  it  had  a  determinate  nature,  the  fact  that  it  had  it 
could  not  be  accounted  for  by  means  of  something  internal 
to  itself,  but  must  be  sought  outside  it.  By  the  theory, 
however,  we  are  prohibited  from  going  outside  the  physical 
world,  since  it  maintains  there  is  nothing  else  than  that 
world.  Hence,  we  must  accept  the  origin  of  the  first  modifica- 
tion as  being  unaccountable,  inexplicable,  and  unintelligible  ; 
and  as  all  the  subsequent  modifications  depend  on  the  first, 
the  whole  process  becomes  entirely  unintelligible. 

Lastly,  the  theory  that  evolution  is  a  process  of  accumula- 
tion of  modifications,  offers  no  explanation  of  the  fact  of  such 
accumulation  in  the  same  direction,  and  does  not  attempt  to 
do  so.  It  is  not,  however,  only  unexplained,  but  in  fact 
inexplicable,  on  the  theory,  for  what  has  to  be  accounted  for 
is  a  series  of  modifications  which  all  tend  in  the  same  specific 
and  determinate  direction.  Now  it  is  clear  that  the  first 
modification  cannot  account  for  others  in  the  same  specific 
direction,  since  these  are  posterior  to,  and  an  addition  to, 
itself  ;  and  at  the  same  time  it  is  denied  that  there  is  any 
other  determination  present  at  the  start,  except  this  first 
modification.  Consequently,  there  is  nothing  at  all  which 
can  account  for  the  accumulation  of  modifications  of  a 
definite  kind,  which  remains  therefore  inexplicable  and 
unintelligible. 

In  a  word,  to  start  with  something  altogether  undifferen- 


TRANSFORMISM  341 

tiated,  indeterminate,  and  homogeneous,  is  to  start  with 
nothing  :  and  from  nothing,  nothing  comes.  This  is  what  a 
theory  of  materialistic  evolution  does  and  must  do,  since  to 
start  with  a  determinate  and  differentiated  being  would  be 
to  confess  that  evolution  was  unable  to  explain  this  being, 
and  this  determination,  and  was  therefore  bankrupt.  Evolu- 
tion is  incapable  of  explaining  the  whole  universe,  as  the 
materialists  claim  it  can,  but  at  best  is  only  capable  of 
explaining  the  development  of  parts  of  it. 

In  conclusion,  then,  we  must  shortly  consider  its  ability 
to  do  this. 

First,  we  must  notice  the  distinction  which  is  drawn 
between  natural  and  systematic  species.  From  a  strictly 
metaphysical  point  of  view,  a  natural  species  will  be  one 
which  differs  from  other  things  by  an  essential  difference,  or 
a  collection  of  individuals  having  the  same  essential  proper- 
ties, though  differing  as  regards  accidental  ones.  In  accor- 
dance with  this  definition  we  shall  say  that  man  forms  a 
natural  species,  inasmuch  as  he  has  a  spiritual  soul  or  form, 
whereby  he  is  essentially  differentiated,  or  made  different  in 
kind,  from  all  other  animals.  We  have  further  seen  reason 
to  conclude  that  the  same  holds  good  of  the  lower  animals  as 
distinct  from  plants.  Further  than  this  it  seems  impossible 
to  go  with  any  certainty  from  the  metaphysical  point  of 
view. 

If,  however,  looking  at  the  world  in  this  way,  we  may  not 
be  able  to  distinguish  more  than  three  natural  species,  yet 
it  seems  not  unreasonable,  regarding  the  matter  in  the  con- 
crete, to  say  that  a  natural  species,  in  a  general  and  wider 
sense,  is  a  collection  of  living  individuals  which  preserve  the 
same  powers  and  the  same  type,  by  means  of  generation  one 
from  another. 

To  natural  species,  taken  in  either  of  these  senses,  is 
opposed  systematic  species,  which  is  a  collection  of  indivi- 
duals belonging  to  the  same  natural  species,  which  have 
certain  accidental  characteristics  in  common,  which  charac- 
teristics are  not  found  in  the  other  members  of  the  same 
natural  species. 

There  is,  clearly,  no  reason,  from  a  philosophical  point  of 


342         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

view,  for  refusing  to  admit  the  transformation  of  such 
systematic  species,  since  there  would  be  no  change  of  nature, 
but  merely  one  of  accidental  attributes.  Whether  it  is 
to  be  admitted,  or  not,  depends  therefore  on  the 
weight  of  the  observed  evidence  for,  or  against,  its 
occurrence. 

Considering,  then,  natural  species  in  the  strict  sense,  do 
our  principles  allow  us  to  say  that  they  could  be  transformed? 
There  seems  to  be  nothing  in  them  to  render  it  impossible 
for  we  should  only  have  a  striking  example  of  substantial 
change.  If  we  admit  its  possibility,  however,  we  can  only 
do  so  if  it  is  allowed  that  the  proper  substantial  form  of  the 
inferior  living  thing  is  drawn  out  of  matter,  when  suitably 
disposed  for  the  reception  of  such  a  form,  while  that  of  man, 
being  spiritual,  can  only  come  from  without.  This  last 
proviso  evidently  breaks  the  unity  of  the  evolutionary 
scheme  ;  and  so  robs  it  of  its  chief  aesthetic  charm,  viz.  its 
unification  of  the  whole  material  world  as  proceeding  from 
one  germ  or  source.  But  it  is  to  be  observed  that  it  is  already 
deprived  of  this  attraction  if  we  admit  that  an  absolutely 
homogeneous  and  indeterminate  entity — a  polite  name  for 
nothing — cannot  be  the  source  of  all  that  is.  By  this  admis- 
sion a  dualism  of  the  material  world  and  its  non-physical 
environment  is  introduced.  Since  reason  absolutely  demands 
that  there  should  be  a  break  in  continuity  here,  the  second 
break  owing  to  the  entrance  of  the  spiritual  soul,  loses  its 
importance.  Neither  of  them  is,  however,  acceptable  to 
what  is  called  '  the  scientific  mind  '  ;  and  scientists  have 
generally  found  the  theory,  according  to  which  man's  body 
is  derived  from  other  forms  of  life  while  his  soul  is  not  so 
derived,  as  objectionable  as  a  downright  denial  of  evolution 
as  a  whole. 

Lastly,  if  natural  species,  in  the  strict  sense  of  the  expres- 
sion, could  be  transformed,  it  follows,  a  fortiori,  that  natural 
species,  in  the  wider  sense,  could  be.  In  saying  this,  how- 
ever, we  do  not  affirm  that  they  have  been  ;  for  indeed  the 
scientific  evidence  of  the  transformation  of  such  natural 
species,  as  of  reptiles  into  birds,  seems  to  be  by  no  means 
conclusive.    The  question  of  fact  in  this  regard  is,  therefore, 


TRANSFORMISM  343 

one  which  belongs  properly  to  physical  science  to 
decide.1 

A  conclusion  of  this  indefinite  kind  has  seemed  unsatis- 
factory to  many  Scholastic  philosophers,  and  consequently 
they  have  attempted  to  argue  that  species  differ  in  nature, 
and  that,  therefore,  there  can  be  no  transit  from  one  to 
another.  Both  these  propositions,  however,  are  open  to 
objection,  since  there  seems  to  be  no  test  by  which  we  can 
determine  the  difference  of  essence  as  between,  say,  two 
animals  ;  and,  further,  the  impossibility  of  transit  from  one 
essence  to  another  is  not  proved.  As  Guibert  says  :  '  To 
say  that  living  species  have  not  a  common  origin  because 
they  differ  in  their  essence,  would  be  to  argue  from  the 
unknown.  It  would  be  better  to  say,  if  the  species  have  a 
common  origin,  perhaps  the  differences  between  them  are 
not  essential.  However  difficult  the  problem  of  the  origin 
of  species  may  be,  it  is  without  doubt  more  accessible  than 
that  of  distinction  of  essences.'2 

What  philosophy  can  tell  us,  then,  about  evolution  is 
first,  that  purely  materialistic  evolution  of  the  type  put  for- 
ward by  Haeckel  is  impossible  ;  and,  secondly,  that  any 
theory  of  evolution  which  sets  out  to  give  an  account  of  the 
way  in  which  the  animate  world  has  come  to  be  in  its  present 
state,  and  aims  at  making  such  an  account  satisfactory  from 
the  philosophical  point  of  viev,,  i.e.  as  giving  an  ultimate 
explanation  of  the  whole  matter,  must  take  account  both  of 
teleology  and  purpose,  and  of  the  action  of  the  first  cause. 
On  the  other  hand,  an  evolutionary  theory  might  be  regarded 
as  a  purely  scientific  one,  a  working  scheme  which  covers 
the  facts  known  at  a  particular  time  ;  and  from  this  point 
of  view,  if  it  did  not  find  teleology  and  the  action  of  the  first 
cause  useful  for  such  a  scheme,  it  might,  and  indeed  ought, 
to  omit  them.  In  doing  so,  however,  it  could  not  exclude 
them  from  reality,  but  only  from  the  picture  it  makes  of  the 
world  for  its  own  practical  purposes.    Few  Darwinians  have, 

1  The  evidence  for  and  against  the  transformation  of  natural  species 
is  summarised  by  Monaco,  Prcelectiones  Metaphysics  Specialis,  Pars  II, 
De  Viventibus  seu  Psychologia,  pp.  215-239. 

2  J.  Guibert,  Les  Origines,  translated  by  G.  S.  Whitmarsh  as  In  the 
Beginning,  p.  152. 


344  MODERN   THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

in  fact,  been  content  with  this  modest  programme,  but 
finding,  or  at  least  considering  that  they  had  found,  that  these 
concepts  were  unnecessary  in  the  construction  of  a  simple 
all-inclusive  and  homogeneous  scheme  of  the  action  and 
development  of  living  organisms,  they  have  jumped  to  the 
conclusion  that  they  had  no  place  in  life  as  lived,  instead  of 
concluding  that  they  had  no  place  in  life  as  conceived  in  a 
particular  scientific  picture.  The  world  of  life,  as  lived,  is 
fuller  and  more  solid  than  the  picture  which  biological  science 
is  able  to  paint  of  it  ;  for  the  reason  that  biology,  of  its  very 
nature,  can  take  account  only  of  its  proximate  causes,  and 
not  of  its  ultimate  nature  and  ground.  When  these  are  also 
considered  we  see  that  it  must  be  set  against  a  background 
of  life  underived  and  self-sufficing,  a  background  which  is 
unchanging  and  eternal. 


Conclusion. 

This  reflection  leads  us  on  to  consider  what  ultimate 
truths  reason  can  extract  from  the  material  provided  by 
observation  of  the  physical  world,  a  subject  which  is  dis- 
cussed in  Metaphysics  ;  the  last  great  branch  or  genus  of  the 
philosophical  sciences  ;  and  it  is  to  this  science  of  meta- 
physics that  we  are  now  to  direct  our  attention. 

Before  doing  so,  it  may  be  convenient  to  glance  down  the 
ladder  of  being  which  we  have  been  ascending,  and  notice 
its  principal  steps  ;  which  are  all  concerned,  in  different 
ways,  with  the  problem  of  multiplicity  and  unity,  of  the 
many  and  the  one,  of  potency  and  act. 

Thus,  we  saw  that  the  endeavours  made  both  by  mechan- 
ism and  dynamism  to  reduce  the  material  world  to  a  simple 
unity  were  unsuccessful ;  and  that  we  must  recognise  in  it  a 
double  multiplicity,  that  of  nature,  and  that  of  the  indivi- 
dual. We  saw  that  the  material  world  is  composed  of  a  large 
number  of  bodies  which  differ  essentially  ;  the  element 
which  thus  specifically  differentiates  them  from  others 
being  the  same  as  that  which  causes  them  to  be  essential 
unities  in  themselves,  viz.  their  form  or  act.  Many  of  them, 
however,  are  not  simple  unities,  but  combine,  with  unity  of 


TRANSFORMISM  345 

nature,  great  heterogeneity  of  accident  or  quality  ;  and  thus 
have  a  certain  organisation  ;  and  may  be  called  organic. 
The  individual,  on  the  other  hand,  considered  merely  as  an 
individual,  is  a  simple  unity,  but  a  negative  one,  inasmuch  as 
its  unity  consists  in  its  distinction  from  all  other  individuals  ; 
which  distinction  is  due  to  the  material  element  in  it.  Here, 
then,  matter  is  the  source  of  unity,  though  a  unity  of  a 
negative  kind. 

With  reference  to  the  next  step  in  the  ladder,  that  of 
quantitative  being,  we  found  that  the  abstract  continuum  is 
composed  of  parts  which  are  not  actual  in  it,  but  potential 
only,  though  the  physical  continuum  is  actually  multiple. 
These  considerations  found  an  application  in  the  two  special 
forms  of  the  continuum  which  we  call  space  and  time. 
Passing  to  the  next  step  we  found  again  a  multiplicity  in 
unity.  The  more  complicated  forms  of  inanimate  things 
having  already  exhibited  a  certain  material  organisation,  as 
soon  as  we  enter  the  world  of  living  things  we  observe  a 
formal  organisation  whereby  living  things  move  themselves, 
one  part  moving  another.  These  things,  then,  are,  in  a 
fuller  sense,  organisms.  This  organisation  does  not,  how- 
ever, interfere  with  their  natural  or  essential  unity.  At  the 
same  time,  there  is  not  unity  of  nature,  of  form  or  act,  all 
through  the  animate  world  ;  but  we  saw  reason  to  dis- 
tinguish at  least  three  natures  among  living  things,  those  of 
plants,  of  animals,  and  of  man.  As  we  rise  thus  in  the  scale 
of  being,  we  find  unity  becoming  more  prominent,  and 
multiplicity  of  nature  less  so.  There  is  more  of  act  and  less 
of  potency,  and,  moreover,  the  forms  of  the  two  higher 
grades  of  life,  the  animal  and  human,  possess  in  their  unity 
the  perfections  of  the  lower  ;  man  thus,  by  means  of  his 
spiritual  soul,  being  a  sort  of  epitome  of  the  whole  material 
creation.  A  further  unification  is  introduced  into  the  world 
of  living  things  by  means  of  knowledge,  the  knower  and  the 
known  being  joined  in  the  closest  of  all  unions,  so  that  the 
soul  is  '  in  a  certain  way  '  all  things.  The  soul  of  man, 
moreover,  being  spiritual,  introduces  us  into  a  world  which 
is  immaterial ;  and  as,  in  a  sense,  the  more  complex  material 
substances  lead  us  up  to  the  organisms  found  in  the  world  of 


346         MODERN  THOMISTIC   PHILOSOPHY 

life,  so  man,  being  formally  spiritual,  leads  us  up  to  that  of 
immaterial  being.  He  is  thus  a  denizen  of  two  worlds,  the 
material  and  the  immaterial ;  the  second  of  which  is  con- 
sidered in  the  science  which  deals  with  being  as  such,  viz. 
Metaphysics,  the  explanation  of  which  is  to  form  the  subject 
of  our  second  volume. 


END    OF    VOLUME    I 


Date  Due 

JAN  1  5  ^M  1  3  53 

MR  2  5  549IAY  3  0  "fffl 

APR28'5fe 

MAY  2  5  -5e 

iAYSo 

junjm*  * 

WW 

.viAR  3 1  *ee  1 

I    IMAR1  c 

'62 

t    1W^ 

ttl    '64 

If**    '* 

SEP  .  .. 

.3 

i 

i 
1 

85 

4 


w 


3  ^  oqe% 


M 


saso 


I/.  /