Skip to main content

Full text of "The Monist"

See other formats


THE  MONIST 


A  QUARTERLY  MAGAZINE 


DEVOTED  TO  THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  SCIENCE 


VOLUME  XXII. 


CHICAGO 

THE  OPEN  COURT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY 
1912 


NT 


l    <A  </V 


COPYRIGHT  BY 

THE  OPEN  COURT  PUBLISHING  Co. 
1911-1912 


-ftt 


CONTENTS  OF  VOLUME  XXII. 

ARTICLES  AND  AUTHORS. 

PACK 

Alexander,  Hartley  Burr.    The  Mystery  of  Life  (Poem) 361 

Andrews,  W.  S.  and  L.  S.  Frierson.    Notes  on  the  Construction  of  Magic 

Squares 304 

Anti-Intellectual  Movement  of  To-day,  The.     By  Paul  Carus  397 

Arreat,  Lucien.    Alfred  Binet  (Obituary)  158 

Atomic  Theories  of  Energy.    By  Arthur  E.  Bostwick 580 

Attention.     By  Eugenio  Rignano  I 

Automatism.     By  Stewart  P.  Foltz   91 

Bergson  and  Religion.    By  James  G.  Townsend  392 

Bergson,  Kant  and.     By  Dr.  Bruno  Jordan  404 

Bergson,  Pragmatism  and  Schopenhauer.    By  Giinther  Jacoby 593 

Bergson,  The  Philosophy  of.    By  Bertrand  Russell 321 

Binet,  Alfred  (Obituary) .    By  Lucien  Arreat 158 

Bostwick,  Arthur  E.    Atomic  Theories  of  Energy 580 

Bradley,  The  Rev.  James,  on  the  Motion  of  the  Fixed  Stars 268 

Buddhism  and  Christianity,  Postscript  on.    By  Richard  Garbe 478 

Buddhism,  Contributions  of  Christianity  to.    By  Richard  Garbe 161 

Buddhist  Loans  to  Christianity.    By  Albert  J.  Edmunds 129,  636 

Buddhist  Research,  The  Progress  of.    By  Albert  J.  Edmunds 633 

Capture  Hypothesis  of  T.  J.  J.  See.    By  H.  Poincare 460 

Capture  Theory  of  Cosmical  Evolution.    By  T.  J.  J.  See 618 

Carus,  Paul. 

The  Anti-Intellectual  Movement  of  To-day  397 

Gellert's   Philosophical   Poetry    124 

Magic  Squares  by  Reversion 159 

A  New  Theory  of  Invention  314 

The  Philosophy  of  Relativity   540 

Poincare' s   Cosmogonic   Hypotheses    480 

The  Principle  of  Relativity  188 

Chance.    By  Henri  Poincare  31 

Chatley,  Herbert.    Two  Studies  in  Suggestion  82 

Christian  Science;  Mind  Cure;  New  Thought.    By  James  H.  Leuba 348 

Christianity,  Buddhist  Loans  to.     By  Albert  J.  Edmunds  129 

Christianity,  Postscript  on  Buddhism  and.     By  R.  Garbe  478 

Christianity  to  Buddhism,  Contributions  of.    By  Richard  Garbe 161 


IV  THE  MONIST. 

FACE 

Couturat,  Louis.     For  Logistics   481 

Edmunds,  Albert  J.    Buddhist  Loans  to  Christianity,  129,  636 ;  The  Prog- 
ress of  Buddhist  Research,  633. 
Edmunds  vs.  Garbe:   ist  Century  Intercourse  between  India  and  Rome. 

By  Wilfred  H.  Schoff  138 

First   Century   Intercourse   between   India   and   Rome.     By  Wilfred   H 

Schoff 138 

Fixed  Stars,  On  the  Motion  of.    By  the  Rev.  James  Bradley 268 

Foltz,  Stewart  P.     Automatism  91 

Frierson,  L.  S.  and  W.  S.  Andrews.    Notes  on  the  Construction  of  Magic 

Squares 304 

Garbe,  Richard.     Contributions  of  Christianity  to  Buddhism,  161 ;  Post- 
script on  Buddhism  and  Christianity,  478. 
Garbe,  Edmunds  vs. :  ist  Century  Intercourse  between  India  and  Rome. 

By  Wilfred  H.  Schoff  138 

Gellert's  Philosophical  Poetry.    By  Paul  Carus 124 

Gilchrist,  Edward.  The  Weird  of  Love  and  Death  (Poem  with  Introduc- 
tion)    257 

India  and  Rome,   First  Century  Intercourse  between.     By  Wilfred  H. 

Schoff 138 

Indo-Roman  Relations  in  the  First  Century,  A  Postscript  to.    By  Wilfred 

H.  Schoff  637 

Invention,  A  New  Theory  of  314 

Inventors  I  Have  Met.     By  Ernst  Mach  230 

Jacoby,  Gunther.    Henri  Bergson,  Pragmatism  and  Schopenhauer 593 

Jordan,  Dr.  Bruno.     Kant  and  Bergson  404 

Jourdain,  Philip  E.  B.  Henri  Poincare:  Obituary,  611;  Maupertuis  and 
the  Principle  of  Least  Action,  414;  Mr.  Bertrand  Russell's  First 
Work  on  the  Principles  of  Mathematics,  149 ;  The  Principle  of  Least 
Action  (Remarks  on  Mach's  Mechanics),  285. 

Kant  and  Bergson.    By  Dr.  Bruno  Jordan 404 

Least  Action,  Maupertuis  and  the  Principle  of.    By  Philip  E.  B.  Jourdain.  414 
Least  Action,  The  Principle  of   (Mach's  Mechanics).     By  Philip  E.  B. 

Jourdain 285 

Leuba,  James  H.     Psychotherapic  Cults:  Christian  Science;  Mind  Cure; 

New  Thought 348 

Logics,  The  New.    By  Henri  Poincare  ' 243 

Logisticians,  The  Latest  Efforts  of  the.    By  Henri  Poincare  524 

Logistics,  For.     By  Louis  Couturat  481 

Mach,  Ernst.    Inventors  I  Have  Met  230 

Mach's  Mechanics,  Remarks  on.    By  Philip  E.  B.  Jourdain  285 

Magic  Squares  by  Reversion.     By  Paul  Carus 159 

Magic  Squares,  Notes  on  the  Construction  of.     By  Harry  Sayles  472 

Magic  Squares,  Notes  on  the  Construction  of.     By  W.  S.  Andrews  and 

L.   S.  Frierson 304 

Mathematics,  Mr.  Bertrand  Russell's  First  Work  on  the  Principles  of. 

By  Philip  E.  B.  Jourdain 149 

Maupertuis  and  the  Principle  of  Least  Action.    By  Philip  E.  B.  Jourdain.  414 
Mystery  of  Life,  The  (Poem).    By  Hartley  Burr  Alexander  361 


CONTENTS  OF  VOLUME  XXII.  V 

PAGE 

Planck,  C.    The  Theory  of  Reversions  53 

Poincare,  Henri.    Chance,  31;  The  Capture  Hypothesis  of  T.  J.  J.  See, 
460;  The  Latest  Efforts  of  the  Logisticians,  524;  The  New  Logics, 

243. 

Poincare,  Henri :  An  Appreciation.    By  William  Benjamin  Smith 615 

Poincare,  Henri :  Obituary.    By  Philip  E.  B.  Jourdain  6n 

Poincare's  Cosmogonic  Hypotheses  480 

Pragmatism  and  Schopenhauer,  Henri  Bergson.    By  Giinther  Jacoby 593 

Psychotherapic  Cults :  Christian  Science ;  Mind  Cure ;  New  Thought.    By 

James  H.  Leuba   348 

Relativity,  The  Philosophy  of.    By  Paul  Carus  540 

Relativity,  The  Principle  of.     By  Paul  Carus  188 

Reversion,  Magic  Squares  by.    By  Paul  Carus  159 

Reversions,  The  Theory  of.     By  C.  Planck  53 

Rignano,  Eugenic.     Attention  i 

Rome  and  India,  First  Century  Intercourse  between.     By  Wilfred  H. 

Schoff  138 

Russell,  Bertrand.     The  Philosophy  of  Bergson   321 

Russell's,  Mr.  Bertrand,  First  Work  on  the  Principles  of  Mathematics.  By 

Philip  E.  B.  Jourdain    149 

Sayles,  Harry.    Notes  on  the  Construction  of  Magic  Squares 472 

Schoff,  Wilfred  H.    First  Century  Intercourse  Between  India  and  Rome 

(Edmunds  vs.  Garbe),  138;  A  Postscript  to  Indo-Roman  Relations 

in  the  First  Century,  637. 

Schopenhauer,  Bergson,  and  Pragmatism.    By  Giinther  Jacoby 593 

See,  T.  J.  J.    The  Capture  Theory  of  Cosmical  Evolution 618 

See,  T.  J.  J.,  The  Capture  Hypothesis  of.    By  H.  Poincare 460 

Smith,  William  Benjamin.    Henri  Poincare:  An  Appreciation  615 

Suggestion,  Two  Studies  in.    By  Herbert  Chatley 82 

Townsend,  James  G.    Bergson  and  Religion  392 

Weird  of  Love  and  Death  (Poem).    By  Edward  Gilchrist 257 

BOOK  REVIEWS   AND   NOTES. 

Apelt,  Dr.  Otto  (Tr.).     Platons  Dialog  Theatet  320 

Baensch,  Otto  (Tr.).    Baruch  de  Spinoza,  Ethik  320 

Baumann,  Julius  (Ed.).     Wolffsche  Begriffsbestimmungen   320 

De  Vries,  Hugo  640 

Engelmeyer,  P.  K.  von.    Der  Dreiakt 314 

Fawcett,  Edward  Douglas.    The  Individual  and  Reality  317 

Hegel,  G.  W.  F.    The  Phenomenology  of  Mind 318 

Heymans,  G.    Das  kiinftige  Jahrhundert  der  Psychologic  319 

M'Giffert,  Arthur  Cushman.     Protestant  Thought  Before  Kant 318 

Molee,  Elias.     Altutonish   640 

Monists,  A  New  Society  of  320 

Nernst,  Prof.  W.     Traite  de  chimie  generate  320 

Pieron,  Henri.     L'evolution  de  la  memoire  ,  319 

Poincare,  H.    Lemons  sur  les  hypotheses  cosmogoniques  480 

Rupp,  Julius.    Ueber  Klassiker  und  Philosophen  der  Neuzeit 318 

Schoff,  Wilfred  H.    The  Periplus  of  the  Erythraean  Sea 317 


VI  THE  MONIST. 

PAGE 

Schubert,  Johannes  (Ed.).  Wilhelm  von  Humboldts  ausgewahlte  philo- 

sophische  Schriften  . 320 

Spranger,  Edouard  (Ed.).  Fichte,  Schleiermacher,  Steffens  iiber  das 

Wesen  der  Universitat  320 

Thomsen,  Anton  .  David  Hume,  hans  liv  og  hans  filosofi 319 

Tiele,  C.  P.    The  Religion  of  the  Iranian  Peoples  639 


1 

VOL.  XXII.  JANUARY,  1912.  NO.  i 

THE  MONIST 


ATTENTION.1 

AFFECTIVE  CONFLICT  AND  UNITY   OF  CONSCIOUSNESS. 

A  LTHOUGH  attention  may  boast  of  possessing  more 
JL~\  abundant  literature  than  any  other  psychical  phe- 
nomenon, yet  it  is  still  far  from  being  fully  explained ;  that 
is  to  say,  it  has  not  been  brought  to  any  extent  into  rela- 
tion and  association  with  other  psychic  phenomena,  espe- 
cially with  those  to  which  it  is  most  closely  related.  And 
although  attention,  as  Titchener  rightly  emphasizes,  forms 
the  very  pivot  upon  which  all  psychology  hinges,  yet  to-day 
the  question  as  to  its  inmost  nature  is  still  very  far  from 
solution.  What  a  great  loss  this  branch  of  science  suffers 
thereby  it  is  easy  to  conceive. 

The  cause  of  this  delinquency  in  the  scientific  explana- 
tion of  attention  holds  true  also  for  all  other  psychic  activi- 
ties, namely,  that  the  investigation  of  all  these  phenomena 
has  been  begun  at  just  the  point  where  they  are  the  most 
complex  and  intricate  instead  of  beginning  with  the  sim- 
plest forms.  The  question  of  attention  has  usually  been 
taken  up  by  means  of  self-contemplation  and  at  the  moment 
of  philosophical  reflection,  instead  of  by  observing,  for 
instance,  the  beast  of  prey,  impatient  to  fall  upon  the 
quarry  he  has  espied  and  for  which  he  has  long  lain  in  wait, 
or  the  child  who  would  fain  put  a  white  pellet  in  his  mouth 
but  is  in  doubt  whether  it  is  a  piece  of  candy  as  usual,  or 
may  turn  out  to  be  a  bitter  pill  as  was  yesterday  the  case. 

1  Translated  from  the  German  which  is  to  appear  in  the  Archiv  fur  Psy- 
cho logie. 


2  THE   MONIST. 

The  expediency  of  beginning  the  investigation  with 
the  simplest  forms  involves  the  expediency  of  pursuing  the 
phylogenetic  method  and  following  the  course  of  evolu- 
tion back  as  far  as  possible  in  order  to  reveal  the  phe- 
nomenon in  the  very  moment  of  its  first  appearance.  This 
is  the  course  we  pursued  when  investigating  the  inmost 
nature  of  another  psychic  phenomenon  no  less  important 
and  fundamental,  namely  that  of  affective  tendencies,  and 
the  phylogenetic  research  which  showed  us  their  mnemonic 
origin  and  nature  at  once  threw  light  upon  that  class  of 
phenomena  previously  so  obscure.2 

We  believe  that  this  procedure  will  attain  the  same 
success  in  our  study  of  attention,  which  however  as  we 
shall  see  is  only  a  secondary  phenomenon  directly  derived 
from  affective  tendencies. 

In  the  treatise  just  mentioned,  "On  the  Mnemonic  Ori- 
gin and  Nature  of  Affective  Tendencies/'  we  have  seen 
that  these  tendencies  are  originally  only  expressions  of  one 
and  the  same  intrinsic  tendency  of  the  organism  to  pre- 
serve or  restore  the  state  of  its  physiological  equilibrium, 
or  to  reestablish  a  previous  physiological  state  which  had 
been  determined  in  the  past  by  certain  environmental  re- 
lations. As  soon  as  these  relations  are  even  partially  re- 
peated they  bring  about  the  "discharge"  of  the  mnemonic 
accumulation  which  this  former  physiological  system  had 
left  behind. 

Then  from  these  affective  tendencies  of  direct  mne- 
monic origin  which  strive  to  reestablish  certain  environ- 
mental relations  as  a  whole,  arise,  according  to  the 
known  law  of  affective  transference  of  the  whole  to  the 

2  E.  Rignano,  "Dell'  origine  e  natura  mnemonica  delle  tendenze  affettive," 
Scientia,  No.  XVII,  i,  1911;  "Ueber  die  mnemonische  Entstehung  und  die 
mnemonische  Natur  affektiver  Neigungen,"  Archiv^  fur  die  gesamte  Psycho- 
logic, Vol.  XX,  No.  i,  191 1 ;  "On  the  Mnemonic  Origin  and  Nature  of  Affec- 
tive Tendencies,"  Monist,  July,  1911.  This  treatise  later  appeared  also  as 
Appendix  to  the  English  edition  of  the  author's  work,  On  the  Inheritance  of 
Acquired  Characters;  An  Hypothesis  of  Heredity,  Development  and  Assimi- 
lation. Chicago,  The  Open  Court  Publishing  Company,  1911. 


ATTENTION.  3 

part,  all  the  other  affective  tendencies  of  indirect  mne- 
monic origin  which  strive  to  reestablish  only  very  definite 
parts  or  details  of  these  environmental  relations.  Besides 
the  most  important  environmental  relations  usually  striven 
for  eagerly  in  their  original  totality,  the  higher  animals, 
and  especially  mankind,  always  possess  a  large  number  of 
secondary  and  even  quite  specific,  environmental  relations 
which  in  this  way  are  capable  of  becoming  in  their  turn 
objects  of  desire. 

At  this  point  we  must  emphasize  the  fact  that  when  a 
physiological  system  has  been  disturbed  by  altered  environ- 
mental conditions  and  reduced  to  a  potential  state  in  the 
form  of  a  mnemonic  accumulation,  it  can  become  fully  re- 
activated and  continue  active  in  a  stable  physiological  state 
only  when  its  internal  and  external  relations  are  en- 
tirely and  exactly  the  same  as  when  they  induced  this 
physiological  state.  Thus  the  physiological  system  of  an 
infusorian  which  has  previously  lived  in  a  certain  tempera- 
ture or  in  a  salt  solution  of  a  certain  proportion  will  gen- 
erate an  affective  tendency  toward  return  to  its  former 
habitat  as  soon  as  it  is  removed  to  other  environmental 
relations ;  and  this  tendency  will  be  expressed  by  negative 
reactions  to  every  other  change  of  its  environmental  rela- 
tions which  tends  to  remove  it  still  further  from  its  original 
habitat,  and  by  positive  reactions  to  every  change  which 
brings  it  nearer  to  its  former  habitat  (Jennings).  But  the 
original  physiological  state  can  not  be  perfectly  reestab- 
lished and  made  to  persist  in  regular  activity  until  the 
little  animal  by  its  own  movements  has  succeeded  in  getting 
again  into  an  environment  identical  with  the  former  one. 

Likewise  the  diminution  of  histogenetic  substance  in 
the  blood  which  prevents  the  continuance  of  the  metabolic 
state  hitherto  active  and  stable,  will  provoke  the  affective 
tendency  of  hunger  and  all  the  acts  of  seeking  and  absorb- 
ing nourishment  proceeding  therefrom;  but  the  normal 


4  THE    MONIST. 

metabolic  state  can  not  be  completely  reestablished  until 
hunger  is  allayed ;  that  is  to  say,  until  the  acts  carried  on 
for  the  purpose  of  seeking  and  absorbing  nourishment  and 
the  processes  of  digestion  have  endowed  the  blood  with 
the  same  intrinsic  quality,  hence  the  same  proportion  of 
histologic  substance,  as  formerly. 

As  with  all  mnemonic  evocations  in  general,  a  small 
part  of  a  certain  former  complex  environmental  state  is 
sufficient,  if  not  to  "satisfy"  the  associated  affective  tend- 
ency, at  least  to  "discharge"  it.  That  is  why  the  sen- 
sations in  so  far  as  they  represent  parts  of  environmental 
conditions,  become  in  a  very  special  manner  the  "dis- 
chargers" of  affective  tendencies.  But  in  this  respect  there 
is  an  essential  difference  between  the  "non-distance  recep- 
tors" and  the  "distance-receptors"  which  Sherrington 
rightly  emphasizes,  so  that  a  very  significant  phylogenetic 
advance  was  made  when  the  latter  gradually  developed 
from  the  former.  For  the  non-distance  receptors  (senses 
with  direct  contact)  usually  permit  the  immediate  or  al- 
most immediate  satisfaction  of  the  affective  tendencies 
which  they  "discharge."  Frequently  the  sensation  dis- 
charging a  certain  affective  tendency  is  identical  with  its 
satisfaction.  On  the  other  hand  the  "distance-receptors" 
usually  produce  that  particular  state  in  which  an  affective 
tendency  is  discharged  and  held  in  suspense,  and  which 
we  are  now  ready  to  investigate. 

"Between  touch  and  assimilation,"  says  Spencer,  "there 
exists  in  the  lowest  creature  an  intimate  connection.  In 
many  Rhizopods  the  tactual  surface  and  the  absorbing  sur- 
face are  coextensive.  The  ameba,  a  speck  of  jelly  having 
no  constant  form,  sends  out  in  this  or  that  direction  pro- 
longations of  its  substance.  One  of  these  meeting  with 
and  attaching  itself  to  some  relatively  fixed  object,  becomes 
a  temporary  limb  by  which  the  body  of  the  creature  is 
drawn  forward;  but  if  this  prolongation  meets  with  some 


ATTENTION.  5 

relatively  small  portion  of  organic  matter  it  slowly  ex- 
pands its  extremity  around  this,  slowly  contracts,  and 
slowly  draws  the  nutritive  morsel  into  the  mass  of  the 
body,  which  collapses  around  it  and  presently  dissolves  it. 
That  is  to  say,  the  same  portion  of  tissue  is  at  once  arm, 
hand,  mouth,  and  intestine — shows  us  the  tactual  and  ab- 
sorbent function  united  in  one/'3 

Sherrington  in  his  turn  says :  "Animal  behavior  shows 
clearly  that  in  regard  to  these  two  groups  of  receptors  the 
one  subserves  differention  of  reaction,  i.  e.,  swallowing 
or  rejection,  of  material  already  found  and  acquired,  e.  g., 
within  the  mouth.  The  other,  the  distance-receptor,  smell, 
initiates  and  subserves  far-reaching  complex  reactions  of 
the  animal  anticipatory  to  swallowing,  namely,  all  that 
train  of  reaction  which  may  be  comprehensively  termed 
the  quest  for  food.  The  latter  foreruns  and  leads  up  to 
the  former.  This  precurrent  relation  of  the  reaction  of 
the  distance-receptor  to  the  non-distance  receptor "  (as 
well  as  the  'conative  feeling'  which  the  distance-receptor 
induces)  "are  typical."4 

Accordingly  non-distance-receptors  occasion  no  "sus- 
pended" affective  tendencies,  no  "conative  feeling,"  but 
instead  they  bring  about  the  immediate  satisfaction  of 
affective  tendencies  at  the  moment  they  are  discharged,  or 
the  immediate  accomplishment  of  the  acts  contributing  to 
their  satisfaction  ("final  or  consummatory  reactions,"  as 
Sherrington  expresses  it).  Distance  -  receptors,  on  the 
other  hand,  discharge  the  affective  tendency  involved  and 
keep  it  active  during  the  entire  time  of  expectation  and 
during  the  whole  series  of  acts  required  of  the  animal  be- 
fore it  can  carry  out  the  last  consummatory  act  which  is 
to  satisfy  this  affective  tendency.  Therefore  in  general 

"Herbert  Spencer,  The  Principles  of  Psychology,  4th  ed.,  Vol.  I,  p.307. 
London,  Williams  and  Norgate. 

*  C.  S.  Sherrington,  The  Integratvue  Action  of  the  Nervous  System,  page 
326  f.  London,  Constable,  1906. 


6  THE  MONIST. 

only  the  distance-receptors  but  not  the  non-distance-recep- 
tors can  bring  about  a  more  or  less  lasting  condition  of  un- 
fulfilled desire:  "If  all  motive  impulses  could  be  at  once 
followed  up  desire  would  have  no  place/'3 

Now  the  question  arises  how  can  we  explain  the  fact 
that  the  affective  tendencies  discharged  or  evoked  by  the 
distance-receptors,  nevertheless  remain  "suspended' ';  in 
other  words,  how  is  it  that  although  they  have  been  evoked 
and  persist  in  this  state,  yet  for  a  long  time  they  occasion 
no  actual  performance  of  any  of  those  consummatory  acts 
which  to  be  sure  would  not  now  have  any  result  but  to 
which  they  nevertheless  impel,  as  is  shown  by  the  incipient 
performance  of  these  acts?  The  beast  of  prey,  for  in- 
stance, whose  appetite  is  aroused  from  afar  by  the  scent 
and  sight  of  his  victim  coming  towards  him  without  pre- 
sentiment of  danger  and  is  whetted  constantly  more  and 
more,  nevertheless  does  not  bound  at  once  toward  the 
longed-for  victim,  but  waits  motionless  and  trembling  with 
all  the  muscles  tense,  until  the  poor  victim  has  come  within 
springing  distance.  What  then  prevents  the  affective  tend- 
ency so  evoked  from  being  at  once  completely  discharged 
in  the  consummatory  act  of  springing  upon  the  prey  and 
tearing  it  to  pieces? 

This  can  only  be  the  counteraction  of  a  conflicting 
tendency  by  which  the  first  tendency  is  prevented  from 
accomplishing  its  consummatory  act.  And  the  conflicting 
tendency  in  this  case  can  be  only  the  combined  result  of  all 
consummatory  acts  which  were  actually  performed  in  the 
past  at  the  first  awakening  of  the  affective  tendency,  but 
every  time  without  result.  Accordingly  we  may  make  the 
assertion  that  it  was  the  "deception''  at  each  premature 
activation  of  the  affective  tendency  called  forth  by  the  dis- 

8  A.  Bain,  The  Emotions  and  the  Will,  4th  ed,  p.  423.  London,  Long- 
mans Green,  1899. 


ATTENTION.  7 

tance-receptor,  which  called  into  being  the  opposite  tend- 
ency by  which  the  other  is  now  held  in  suspense. 

A  familiar  instance  is  Mobius's  experiment  with  the 
pike.  By  means  of  a  pane  of  glass  he  divided  a  large  glass 
bowl  full  of  water  into  two  parts.  In  one  side  he  placed 
the  pike  and  in  the  other  he  put  tiny  whitings  which  pro- 
vide the  pike's  customary  food.  It  now  happened  that 
whenever  the  pike  dived  after  one  of  the  small  fishes  he 
fell  against  the  obstructing  pane  of  glass.  For  a  week  he 
continued  to  make  these  vain  attempts.  Then  he  gave 
up  entirely  the  pursuit  of  his  unattainable  prey  and  did 
not  change  his  behavior  even  when  the  obstructing  pane 
of  glass  had  been  taken  away. 

Now  the  constantly  repeated  deceptions  which  resulted 
when  the  affective  tendency  released  by  a  distance-receptor 
produced  immediately  the  performance  of  a  consummatory 
act  which  was  necessarily  unsuccessful,  must  have  a  very 
similar  effect  on  all  animals  provided  with  these  senses. 
And  so  it  has  come  to  pass  that  the  very  discharge  effected 
by  the  distance-receptors  of  any  affective  tendency  and  the 
premature  beginning  of  the  movement  connected  with  it, 
now,  thanks  to  the  memory  of  former  unsuccessful  at- 
tempts, provoke  the  antagonistic  tendency,  like  that  which 
prevented  the  pike  from  falling  upon  its  prey.  And  this 
conflict  produces  that  state  of  an  affective  tendency  "held 
in  suspense"  which  constitutes  the  state  of  attention. 

Accordingly  we  may  say  that  phylogenetically  atten- 
tion originated  with  the  distance-receptors,  and  that  it  con- 
sists in  the  conflict  of  two  affective  tendencies,  the  second  of 
which  is  "discharged"  by  the  first,  prevents  it  for  a  time 
from  complete  activation  and  hence  keeps  it  "in  suspense." 

The  state  of  attention  therefore  does  not  consist  of  a 
single  affective  state  but  of  the  conflict  of  tendencies  aris- 
ing from  the  coexistence  of  two  affective  states.  It  is  be- 
cause this  fact  has  been  overlooked  that  it  has  not  been  pos- 


8  THE  MONIST. 

sible  heretofore  to  understand  in  what  the  specific  nature 
of  this  state  of  attention  really  consists,  and  so  to  under- 
stand the  real  significance  of  the  holding  of  an  affective 
tendency  "in  suspense"  which  is  characteristic  of  attention, 
nor  to  understand  why  all  those  movements  which  the  first 
of  the  two  affective  tendencies  would  itself  have  provoked 
at  once,  are  arrested  "in  the  nascent  state,"  whereas  had 
this  affectivity  alone  been  active  they  would  have  proceeded 
directly  to  completion. 

But  aside  from  the  case  just  considered  of  a  pre- 
mature performance  of  the  consummatory  act  involved, 
the  distance-receptors  under  many  other  circumstances 
arouse  a  second  affectivity  in  conflict  with  the  first  which 
for  some  time  prevents  the  complete  activation  of  the 
former,  as  a  consequence  of  the  unexpected,  unpleasant 
results  which  had  some  time  previously  been  associated 
with  it.  However  and  whenever  such  an  affective  conflict 
occurs  there  at  once  arises  also  a  corresponding  state  of 
attention;  and  vice  versa,  there  is  no  state  of  attention 
without  such  a  conflict  of  tendencies.  For  we  need  only 
consider  carefully  a  few  of  the  most  significant  cases,  se- 
lected so  as  to  be  as  different  as  possible  from  one  an- 
other, in  order  at  once  to  see  in  operation  this  conflict  of 
tendencies  in  every  state  of  attention. 

"A  young  chick  two  days  old,  for  example,"  says  Lloyd 
Morgan,  "had  learned  to  pick  out  pieces  of  yolk  from 
others  of  white  of  egg.  I  cut  little  bits  of  orange-peel  of  the 
same  sizes  as  the  pieces  of  yolk  and  one  of  these  was  soon 
seized  but  at  once  relinquished,  the  chick  shaking  its  head. 
Seizing  another  he  held  it  for  a  moment  in  the  bill  but  then 
dropped  it  and  scratched  at  the  base  of  his  beak.  That  was 
enough.  He  could  not  again  be  induced  to  seize  a  piece 
of  orange-peel.  The  obnoxious  material  was  now  removed 
and  pieces  of  yolk  of  egg  substituted  but  they  were  left 
untouched,  being  probably  taken  for  orange-peel.  Sub- 


ATTENTION.  9 

sequently  he  looked  at  the  yolk  with  hesitation,  but  pres- 
ently pecked  doubtfully,  not  seizing  but  merely  touching. 
Then  he  pecked  again,  seized,  and  swallowed  it."6 

Accordingly  we  see  here  how  the  first  act  of  attention  of 
the  newly  hatched  chicken  arose  from  the  conflict  between  its 
first  tendency  to  seize  the  yolk  of  the  egg  and  the  conflicting 
tendency  aroused  by  the  memory  of  the  unpleasant  expe- 
rience produced  by  picking  up  the  orange-peel.  The  "effec- 
tive guidance  and  control  of  consciousness,"  of  which  Lloyd 
Morgan  speaks  as  one  factor  which  influenced  the  instinc- 
tive pecking  of  the  chicken,  was  thus  only  the  arousing  of 
a  new  affectivity,  repugnance,  that  inhibited  the  first  affec- 
tivity,  hunger,  which  of  itself  impelled  toward  the  comple- 
tion of  the  instinctive  act.7 

A  little  girl  is  taken  out  walking  by  a  servant.  The 
child  unexpectedly  catches  a  glimpse  of  her  mother  on 
the  other  side  of  the  street  and  wishes  to  run  over  to  her 
at  once.  But  the  maid  warns  her  with  a  cry,  "Look  out 
for  the  carriage!"  and  the  little  one  stops.  The  carriage 
has  hardly  passed  and  she  has  almost  taken  a  step  ahead 
when  another  approaching  vehicle  forces  her  to  give  way 
again.  The  conflict  of  the  two  tendencies  of  hope  and  fear, 
kept  alive  in  the  child  by  the  sight  of  her  mother  and  the 
repeated  passing  of  vehicles,  is  shown  very  clearly  by  the 
direction  of  her  steps  first  forward  and  then  backward. 
It  is  faithfully  reflected  in  the  expression  of  the  small 
bright  eyes  which  shine  with  anticipation  and  joy  as  soon 
as  they  are  turned  upon  her  mother  and  the  child  takes  a 
step  nearer  to  her,  but  at  once  look  anxious  and  confused 
when  they  observe  one  of  the  heavy  wagons  of  which 
there  seems  to  be  no  end.  Finally,  however,  the  street- 
crossing  is  unobstructed.  The  state  of  fear  and  also  the 
"state  of  attention,"  has  entirely  disappeared  so  that  the 

'  Lloyd  Morgan,  Habit  and  Instinct,  p.  40  f.    New  York,  Arnold,  1896. 
7  Lloyd  Morgan,  op.  cit.,  pp.  129-131,  135,  139  f. 


IO  THE  MONIST. 

little  girl  may  at  last  satisfy  her  wish  and  throw  herself 
into  her  mother's  arms. 

The  conflict  of  tendencies  is  likewise  exhibited  with 
great  distinctness  in  certain  typical  states  of  attention 
where  it  is  expressed  in  the  exceedingly  subtle  choices  be- 
tween almost  imperceptible  modalities  of  a  certain  act. 

A  billiard  player,  for  instance,  who  has  already  directed 
his  cue  at  the  ball,  wishes  first  of  all  to  make  a  successful 
stroke.  He  is  ready  to  make  the  stroke  but  the  extreme 
tension  of  the  muscles  in  his  arm  causes  him  to  fear  that 
the  stroke  may  turn  out  to  be  too  strong,  as  it  did  shortly 
before.  In  consequence  of  this  conflicting  affectivity  his 
muscles  become  somewhat  lax.  Nevertheless  the  weaker 
tension  he  now  feels  reawakens  in  him  the  memory  of  an 
earlier  unsuccessful  stroke  when  the  movement  of  the  ball 
had  not  been  swift  enough,  and  now  he  finds  himself  per- 
plexed by  the  opposite  fear  lest  the  stroke  may  be  too  weak. 
By  the  swings  of  his  arm,  now  longer  and  now  shorter, 
which  precede  the  stroke  and  bring  the  point  of  the  cue 
nearer  to  the  ball  or  farther  from  it,  a  spectator  can  discern 
the  rapid  alternation  of  conflicting  affectivities  which  dis- 
charge each  other  and  exaggerate  or  moderate  each  other 
in  order  finally  to  bring  about  the  result  of  giving  to  the 
ball  exactly  the  necessary  force. 

The  same  is  true  when  a  person  who  is  writing  attempts 
to  remove  with  his  finger  a  tiny  hair  from  his  steel  pen. 
This  rarely  succeeds  at  the  first  attempt  because  the  fear 
of  soiling  his  finger-tips  causes  him  to  press  them  together 
before  they  are  near  enough  to  the  point  of  the  pen  and 
the  hair.  The  first  failure  gives  rise  to  care  lest  the  second 
attempt  may  also  fail,  and  this  opposite  fear  partly  sup- 
presses and  moderates  the  fear  of  soiling  the  fingers,  so 
that  the  wish  to  remove  the  hair  by  this  time  lends  to  the 
arm  and  fingers  exactly  the  degree  of  muscular  contraction 


ATTENTION.  II 

necessary  to  get  hold  of  the  extending  end  of  the  hair  with- 
out touching  the  inky  pen. 

From  this  conflict  of  tendencies,  inevitably  occurring 
as  soon  as  we  attempt  to  perform  an  act  "carefully," 
arises  the  well-known  fact  that  attention,  when  directed 
to  actions  which  by  long  practice  have  become  mechanical, 
makes  their  execution  less  rapid  and  perfect  than  if  they 
had  taken  place  quite  automatically. 

"An  automatic  connection  of  contents  or  movements 
has  nothing  to  gain  from  the  intervention  of  attention, — 
nay  suffers  a  very  positive  loss  in  accuracy  and  rapidity 
of  realization,  if  the  attention  be  directed  upon  it."8 

Thus  the  recitation  of  a  poem  which  has  been  learned  so 
well  by  heart  that  it  can  be  repeated  mechanically  becomes 
uncertain  and  hesitating  when  the  speaker  gives  it  his 
whole  attention.  And  a  person  who  writes  his  name  with 
the  greatest  facility  when  he  gives  no  thought  to  it  is  pretty 
sure  to  do  it  disconnectedly  and  without  ease  as  soon  as 
some  one  asks  him  for  his  autograph.  For  in  this  case 
every  stroke  of  the  pen  needs  a  short  preparation  and  re- 
quires a  certain  application  of  the  will  to  begin  and  com- 
plete it,  whereas  the  transference  from  one  stroke  to  an- 
other becomes  studied  and  awkward  instead  of  easy  and 
running  as  usual.9 

Nevertheless  there  are  individual  cases,  even  where 
the  attention  is  greatly  aroused,  in  which  the  conflict  of 
tendencies  appears  less  distinct.  For  instance  in  Sardou's 
drama,  "Tosca,"  we  have  the  scene  where  Tosca's  lover 
is  tortured.  It  arouses  the  keenest  sympathy  and  attention 
of  all  the  spectators.  Where  is  there  any  conflict  of  ten- 
dencies in  this  case?  And  yet  we  shall  find  it  if  we  reflect 
a  little.  On  the  one  hand  there  is  the  tendency,  according 

•O.  Kiilpe,  "The  Problem  of  Attention,"  Monist,  XIII,  p.  61.  Chicago, 
Oct.  1902. 

"H.  Maudsley,  The  Physiology  of  Mind,  p.  520  f.  London,  Macmillan, 
1876.— The  Pathology  of  Mind,  p.  143.  London,  Macmillan,  1895. 


12  THE  MONIST. 

to  the  character  of  the  spectator,  either  to  fall  upon  the 
crafty  Scarpia  and  slay  him,  or  to  throw  oneself  at  his 
feet  and  with  Tosca  beg  his  mercy  for  her  lover;  or  one 
might  hasten  to  the  aid  of  the  unfortunate  man  and  lib- 
erate him  after  driving  away  or  killing  the  agents  of  the 
torturer.  On  the  other  hand  the  cultured  man  has  ac- 
quired a  tendency  by  education  or  custom  to  do  nothing 
which  conventionality  does  not  permit,  and  not  to  make 
himself  ridiculous  by  acts  which  would  be  the  more  ridic- 
ulous since  every  one  knows  that  he  is  not  beholding  a  real- 
ity but  a  mere  invention.  And  that  this  is  really  the  case  is 
proved  by  the  village  theaters  where  the  actor  who  plays 
the  part  of  the  tyrant  is  often  hissed  by  the  public,  and  some- 
times even  becomes  the  target  of  more  or  less  harmless  mis- 
siles thrown  by  the  more  unsophisticated  spectators.  The 
author  once  attended  such  a  spectacle.  Some  conspirators 
were  in  hiding  behind  a  curtain,  waiting  to  kill  the  king, 
who  by  this  time  had  won  the  favor  of  the  public  by  his 
generosity  and  fearlessness.  He  had  hardly  appeared  when 
a  voice  was  heard  to  call  out  at  the  first  movement  of  the 
curtain,  "Look  out,  they  are  going  to  kill  you !"  The  entire 
audience  laughed  uproariously,  and  the  simple  spectator 
was  overcome  with  confusion.  He  will  doubtless  succeed 
another  time  in  repressing  his  magnanimous  outburst, 
thanks  to  the  conflicting  tendency  not  to  make  himself 
again  the  object  of  derision. 

Attention  which  is  aroused  by  novelty  is  likewise  the 
result  of  a  conflict  of  tendencies  arising  from  the  fact  that 
just  because  the  object  is  new,  it  has  not  yet  been  "affec- 
tively classified,"  and  therefore  arouses  both  hope  and 
fear  at  the  same  time. 

If  the  space  at  our  disposal  permitted,  we  could  easily 
show  that  any  "classification"  whatever  is  based  either  di- 
rectly or  indirectly  upon  ah  affective  tendency.  The  prin- 
ciple upon  which  it  rests  consists  originally  in  the  fact  that 


ATTENTION.  13 

no  sensation  or  perception  of  the  distance-receptor  has  any 
value  for  the  organism  except  as  a  symbol  of  a  possible 
environmental  state,  near  or  remote,  to  be  striven  after  or 
avoided.  As  long  as  this  symbol  has  not  been  placed  in 
either  category,  the  conflicting  affectivities  of  hope  and 
fear  oppose  each  other  and  hold  each  other  in  suspense. 
This  opposition  is  seen  distinctly,  for  instance,  in  a  child 
who  is  undecided  whether  or  not  he  should  drink  the  tea 
offered  him  by  his  mother  and  which  this  time  has  an  un- 
usual color,  because  he  is  not  sure  whether  it  is  a  sweet  or 
bitter  draught;  or  in  a  beast  of  prey  that  sees  a  strange 
looking  animal  and  is  in  doubt  whether  it  is  a  dangerous 
enemy  or  perhaps  a  suitable  quarry  and  therefore  makes 
its  muscles  tense,  ready  at  the  same  time  for  either  attack 
or  flight. 

Curiosity  is  only  one  of  the  least  forms  of  this  conflict 
of  tendencies  or  of  this  particular  state  of  attention  pro- 
duced by  novelty.  "The  craving  for  knowledge  in  its  in- 
stinctive form  is  called  curiosity.  It  exists  in  all  degrees, 
from  that  of  the  animal  which  touches  or  smells  an  un- 
known object,  to  the  all-examining,  all-embracing  scrutiny 
of  a  Goethe."  "Curiosity  consists  of  two  questions  ex- 
pressed or  implied:  What  is  it?  What  use  is  it?.  . .  .The 
dog  brought  face  to  face  with  an  unknown  object,  looks 
at  it,  smells  it,  approaches,  withdraws,  ventures  to  touch 
it,  returns,  and  begins  again ;  he  is  pursuing  this  investiga- 
tion after  his  own  fashion ;  he  is  solving  a  double  problem 
of  nature  and  utility."10 

On  the  other  hand  the  "not  new" — and  this  also  may  be 
any  specific  object  when  we  see  it  for  the  first  time — com- 
prises everything  we  know  how  to  classify  in  one  of  our 
various  affective  categories.  It  either  brings  about  imme- 
diately the  evocation  and  satisfaction  of  the  affectivity  con- 

10  Th.  Ribot,  Psychologie  des  sentiments,  pp.  369,  371.  Paris :  Alcan,  1906. 
Second  English  edition,  pp.  368,  370.  London,  Walter  Scott,  1911. 


14  THE  MONIST. 

cerned,  like  the  little  waterfall  in  the  mountain  which  awak- 
ens the  desire  to  drink  from  it;  or  it  evokes  the  affective 
tendency  but  holds  it  in  suspense  for  fear  lest  its  immediate 
complete  satisfaction  might  involve  some  evil  consequences 
as  we  have  previously  seen ;  or  finally  it  may  at  that  moment 
be  altogether  unable  to  evoke  any  tendency,  like  the  sight 
or  odor  of  a  familiar  dish  when  we  have  had  enough.  In 
this  case  the  affective  activity  is  reduced  to  a  minimum, 
the  state  of  attention  entirely  ceases,  and  we  experience 
monotony  or  tedium.  If  this  state  of  minimum  affective 
activity  is  reduced  to  zero,  we  have  the  condition  of  sleep. 
"Sleep,"  as  Bergson  very  truly  says,  "means  to  disinterest 
oneself  (se  desinteresser) .  We  sleep  in  direct  proportion 
to  our  disinterestedness."3 

Finally  there  is  only  a  very  slight  distinction  between 
"curiosity"  and  the  state  of  attention  of  the  investigator. 
The  investigator  observes  a  certain  object  or  a  certain 
phenomenon  in  order  to  convince  himself  whether  this  ob- 
ject or  this  phenomenon  really  proves  to  possess  certain 
properties  whose  presence  has  been  asserted  by  others,  or 
which  he  himself  thought  he  noticed  at  the  first  glance,  or 
which  in  his  opinion  should  exist.  The  presence  or  absence 
of  these  properties  is  of  exceedingly  great  value  to  the 
observer  as  is  apparent  from  the  fact  that  he  applies  him- 
self with  such  great  care  to  observe  them,  for  they  may 
for  instance  confirm  certain  preconceived  theories  or  rep- 
resent a  highly  important  scientific  discovery.  Hence  on 
the  one  hand  he  cherishes  the  ardent  hope  that  the  sup- 
posed properties  would  really  be  found  to  exist.  On  the 
other  hand  he  is  restrained  from  prematurely  making 
known  a  discovery  whose  accuracy  might  later  be  con- 
tested by  other  inquirers  to  the  great  injury  of  his  own 
scientific  prestige.  Just  think  for  instance  with  what  great 

u  H.  Bergson,  "Le  reve,"  Bulletin  de  I'Institut  Psychologique  International, 
p.  118.  Paris,  Alcan,  May  1900. 


ATTENTION.  15 

attention — that  is  to  say,  with  what  great  care  lest  he 
may  have  been  a  victim  of  an  optical  illusion — Schiapa- 
relli  must  have  carried  on  his  ovservations  before  he  de- 
cided to  make  known  his  discovery  of  the  canals  of  Mars. 
Here  too  this  hope  and  this  care  furnish  the  conflict  of  two 
affectivities  without  which  here  as  elsewhere  no  actual 
state  of  attention  would  or  could  be  present. 

As  we  have  by  this  time  come  to  recognize  the  inmost 
nature  of  the  affective  conflict  which,  as  appears  from  the 
few  examples  here  adduced,  is  characteristic  of  every  state 
of  attention,  so  all  other  properties  which  always  accom- 
pany this  state  prove  at  the  same  time  to  be  so  many  simple 
and  direct  consequences  of  its  nature. 

Especially  are  we  able  to  perceive  at  once  the  uncon- 
vincing character  of  Ribot's  definition  of  attention  as  the 
state  of  "relative  monoideism."  We  might  if  necessary  call 
it  a  state  of  "monoaffectivity  held  in  suspense,"  but  as  we 
have  seen,  it  is  still  better  to  define  it  as  a  state  of  "double 
conflicting  affectivity."12 

Ribot's  motor  or  peripheral  theory  proves  to  be  equally 
erroneous :  "Are  the  movements  of  the  face,  the  body  and 
the  limbs,  and  the  respiratory  modifications  that  accompany 
attention,  simply  effects,  outward  marks  as  is  usually  sup- 
posed? Or  are  they,  on  the  contrary,  the  necessary  con- 
ditions, the  consistent  elements,  the  indispensable  factors 
of  attention?  Without  hesitation  we  accept  the  second 
thesis."13 

On  the  other  hand  the  so-called  theories  of  "central 
origin"  seem  to  be  perfectly  correct.14  Attention  is  indeed 
a  "central,"  psychological  phenomenon ;  for  the  awakening 
of  the  primary  or  active  affectivity  and  the  counter-awak- 

12  See  Th.  Ribpt,  Psychologie  de  I'attention,  pp.  6-8,  6th  edition.     Paris 
Alcan,  1902.    English  edition,  p.  10. 

13  Ribot,  op.  cit.,  p.  32.    English  edition,  p.  25. 

14  See,  e.  g.,  J.  Sully,  "The  Psycho- Physical  Process  in  Attention,"  Brain, 
July  1890,  especially  pp.  155-157.     London,  Macmillan.— Vaschide  and  Meu- 
nier,  La  Psychologie  de  I'attention,  pp.  196  f.     Paris,  Blond  ,1910. 


l6  THE  MONIST. 

ening  of  the  secondary  affectivity  which  holds  the  other 
in  suspense,  are  phenomena  of  this  nature.  Attention 
therefore  is  first  of  all  an  essentially  affective  phenomenon 
and  only  indirectly  and  in  a  subordinate  manner  does  it 
become  a  motor  phenomenon  by  the  fact  that  the  awakening 
of  any  affectivity  whatever  always  produces  motor  and 
peripheral  phenomena  which  are  therefore  only  accom- 
panying or  derived  phenomena. 

Ribot's  error  comes  from  the  fact  that  he  has  not  suc- 
ceeded in  correctly  comprehending  the  nature  of  affective 
tendencies,  for  he  sees  very  well  that  "attention  always 
depends  upon  affective  states,"  but  he  adds  soon  after: 
"How  are  we  to  represent  to  ourselves  these  tendencies? 
The  only  positive  idea  that  we  can  get  of  them  is  to  con- 
sider them  as  movements  (or  as  inhibitions  of  movements), 
be  they  real  or  nascent/'13 

Accordingly  for  this  inquirer  the  motor  elements  would 
by  themselves  constitute  the  entire  essence  of  affective 
tendencies.  But  it  is  the  affective  tendencies  which  are  the 
foundation  of  the  motor  elements,  and  the  reverse  is  false. 

As  we  have  seen  in  our  frequently  cited  treatise  "On 
the  Mnemonic  Origin  and  Nature  of  Affective  Tenden- 
cies," an  affective  tendency  is  only  a  gravitation,  so  to 
speak,  toward  that  environment  or  those  environmental 
relations  which  permit  the  reactivation  of  the  mnemonic 
accumulation  constituting  this  affective  tendency.  But  of 
itself,  it  does  not  produce  any  preferential  impulse  toward 
one  rather  than  toward  another  series  of  movements.  For 
even  if  these  movements  were  such  as  could  eventually 
bring  the  organism  back  into  the  desired  environmental 
conditions,  yet  in  themselves  they  have  nothing  to  do  with 
the  ultimate  satisfaction  of  this  affective  tendency.  It  is 
only  when  one  series  of  movements  succeeds  in  bringing 
the  organism  back  to  the  requisite  environmental  condi- 

15  Ribot,  Psychology  of  Attention,  pp.  166,  172.  English  edition,  pp.  112, 116. 


ATTENTION.  17 

tions  sooner  or  better  than  the  others  and  only  from  this 
moment,  that  it  becomes  preferred  to  the  others.  Only 
from  this  moment  will  the  awakening  of  the  affective  ten- 
dency give  rise  to  definite  motor  elements. 

But  before  this  occurs,  that  is  to  say  before  the  affective 
tendency  has  found  preferable  any  one  of  the  movements 
capable  of  leading  to  the  desired  end,  the  affective  tendency 
towards  that  end  will  already  exist.  The  very  fact  of  this 
affective  choice  proves  that  in  point  of  time  the  choosing 
factor  precedes  the  element  chosen,  whence  it  follows  that 
there  can  be  an  affective  tendency  even  in  the  absence  of 
any  motor  element.  For  instance  a  new  and  unusual  in- 
disposition which  may  attack  us  arouses  the  affective  tend- 
ency to  be  freed  from  it,  but  this  does  not  and  cannot 
initiate  any  motion  whatever. 

Hence  if  affective  tendencies  and  motor  elements  are 
two  different  things,  and  if  the  latter  are  based  upon  the 
former  but  not  the  reverse,  then  this  is  also  true  with 
regard  to  attention  for  which  the  motor  elements  are  not 
an  indispensable  condition  but  merely  quite  secondary  phe- 
nomena. 

Since  every  conflict  of  affective  tendencies  is  expressed 
in  a  conflict  of  the  motor  elements  induced  by  them,  so  a 
clear  explanation  is  afforded  even  with  the  "central  origin" 
for  the  fact  that  "muscular  tension/'  "motor  innervation," 
"tonic  contraction,"  and  the  "elevation  of  the  entire  psychic 
life,"  characterize  every  state  of  attention,  as  all  have  ob- 
served.16 

Affective  choice  determines  not  only  the  particular 
movements  of  locomotion,  of  seizing,  etc.,  which  make  for 
the  desired  object,  but  also  the  adjustment  of  the  sense- 
organs,  itself  a  musculo-motor  phenomenon  on  which  de- 
pends the  more  or  less  successful  result  of  the  movements, 

16  Maudsley,  The  Physiology  of  Mind,  p.  313.— Ch.  Fere,  "Physiologic  de 
1'attention,"  Revue  philosophique,  Oct.  1800,  pp.  401, 404. — K.  B.  R.  Aars,  'Ttfotes 
sur  I'attention,"  Annee  psychologique,  VIII,  p.  216.  Paris,  Schleicher,  1902. 


l8  THE  MONIST. 

of  whatever  kind  they  are,  and  in  which  therefore  both  of 
the  two  conflicting  affectivities  cooperate.  Now  for  in- 
stance when  we  are  surprised  by  a  sudden  noise  and  direct 
our  glance  at  once  to  the  distant  object  from  which  it  seems 
to  come,  the  state  of  attention  is  alert  during  the  whole 
interval  preceding  the  moment  in  which  the  eyes  have  be- 
come adjusted  to  the  new  distance,  which  requires  a  certain 
length  of  time  when  the  object-  is  far  away.  Thus  atten- 
tion is  awakened  (here  too  in  conformity  with  the  theory 
of  central  origin)  before  and  not  after  the  adjustment  of 
the  organ  concerned.17 

Since  on  the  other  hand  the  peripheral  sensory  re- 
lations remain  the  same,  the  attention  may  be  directed 
now  to  some  and  now  to  other  sense-perceptions,  just  as 
when,  confined  within  our  room,  we  give  more  heed  to 
certain  noises  in  the  street  than  to  others  which  come  from 
the  same  direction;  for  instance,  to  the  hoof -beat  of  the 
horses  belonging  to  an  equipage  that  stops  before  our 
door,  in  order  to  determine  by  the  sound  which  of  our 
friends  has  come  to  call;  or  to  the  roll  of  the  wheels  in 
order  to  find  out  whether  the  friend  who  has  come  to  take 
us  out  driving  is  riding  in  a  closed  or  open  carriage.  Atten- 
tion may  even  be  directed  to  certain  properties  of  a  sense- 
impression,  for  instance  to  the  strength  or  pitch  of  a  note 
of  music,  or  to  certain  other  characteristics  such  as  its 
timbre.  No  other  examples  could  demonstrate  better  than 
these  how  entirely  attention  is  independent  of  the  ad- 
justment of  the  sense,  as  well  as  in  general  of  every 
other  "peripheral  factor."18 

From  this  "central  origin"  of  attention  which  has  been 
so  fully  established,  and  from  the  inmost  nature  of  the 
opposition  between  two  mutually  conflicting  affectivities 
as  above  discussed,  a  conclusion  of  the  utmost  importance 

"See  W.  B.  Pillsbury,  Attention,  p.  13.  London,  Swan  Sonnenschein, 
1908. 

18  O.  Kiilpe,  loc.  cit.,  p.  50. 


ATTENTION.  IQ 

may  be  drawn,  namely  that  the  object  of  attention  is  ob- 
served simultaneously  from  two  quite  distinct  points  of 
view.  Thus  a  large  number  of  properties  and  character- 
istics, of  advantages  and  disadvantages  are  perceived,  ob- 
served, recalled  and  emphasized,  which  would  by  no  means 
be  the  case  if  only  a  single  affectivity  were  operative. 

Wundt's  well-known  metaphorical  definition  of  the  "ap- 
perception" produced  by  attention  as  consisting  in  the  tran- 
sition of  the  image  "from  the  internal  visual  field  to  the 
internal  visual  point  of  consciousness,"  accordingly,  might 
better  be  replaced  by  that  of  an  internal  double  reflector 
illuminating  the  object  or  the  image  from  several  sides  at 
the  same  time.19 

That  is  why  attention  prevents  the  mnemonic  addition 
of  sensation-evocations,  which  the  affectivity  adds  to  the 
rough  elementary  sensation  at  the  moment  it  is  aroused, 
from  distorting  the  perception  produced  by  this  mnemonic 
contribution  into  an  illusion  or  hallucination,  which  on  the 
contrary  is  always  the  case  when  the  affectivity  thus 
aroused  remains  alone. 

Sudden  and  intense  fear,  for  instance,  makes  any  state 
of  attention  quite  impossible  and  may  give  rise — as  in  the 
classical  case  of  the  wanderer  walking  at  night  through 
a  dense  forest — to  those  characteristic  hallucinations  cited 
and  described  in  all  text-books  of  psychology  and  psycho- 
pathology.  On  the  other  hand  that  man  is  "cold-blooded" 
who  does  not  flee  at  the  sudden  rustling  of  leaves  which 
arouses  in  him  at  the  first  moment  the  vision  of  some  hid- 
den robber  or  dangerous  beast  behind  the  trees,  but  who, 
restrained  by  his  repugnance  to  so  cowardly  an  action, 
looks  around  "with  attention"  to  see  whether  there  really 
is  a  living  creature  there,  and  what  sort  of  a  one  it  is,  or 
whether  indeed  it  was  not  the  wind  that  made  the  noise. 

19  W.  Wundt,  Grundziige  der  physiologischen  Psychologic,  5th  ed.,  VoL 
HI,  p.  333.  Leipsic,  Engelmann,  1903.— Ostwald,  Vorlesungen  iiber  Natur- 
philosophic,  3d  ed.,  pp.  400,  403.  Leipsic,  Veit,  1905. 


2O  THE  MONIST. 

Likewise  in  a  state  of  passion  any  attention  to  all 
that  is  connected  with  this  passion  becomes  impossible  and 
the  passionate  man  is  therefore  exposed  to  all  the  auto- 
suggestions and  hallucinations  of  an  Othello  because  of  the 
very  singleness  of  the  control  by  the  hypertrophic  affective 
tendency  characteristic  of  this  state.  In  monomaniacs  also 
as  well  as  in  those  suffering  from  a  chronic  persecution- 
mania  and  similar  psychical  diseases,  the  thing  lacking  is 
the  counter-affectivity  which  would  tend  to  make  them 
fear  that  they  were  making  a  mistake.  They  are  mono- 
affective  in  the  proper  sense  of  the  word,  therefore  in- 
capable likewise  of  a  real  and  proper  state  of  attention. 

The  absence  of  any  counter-affectivity  produces  in  all 
these  cases  a  total  absence  of  "opposing  inhibitors,"  as 
Taine  would  say,  which  could  inhibit  the  auto-suggestions 
and  hallucinations  produced  by  the  one  existing  affectivity, 
and  permit  the  latter  to  reign  unhindered  and  exclusively. 
On  the  other  hand,  great  attention  always  protects  from 
suggestion  practised  by  others  just  because  the  opposite 
affectivity,  the  fear  of  being  deceived,  becomes  very  strong, 
as  is  proved  for  instance  by  Binet's  experiments  on  the 
susceptibility  of  school  children  to  suggestion.20 

*      *      * 

Now  as  we  pass  to  the  relations  existing  between  atten- 
tion and  consciousness  we  must  first  briefly  mention  our 
theory  with  regard  to  the  conditions  which  determine  the 
consciousness  and  those  which  determine  the  unconscious- 
ness of  the  different  psychic  states.21 

In  the  above  mentioned  treatise  we  have  come  to  the 
conclusion  that  a  given  psychic  state  is  neither  conscious 
nor  unconscious  in  itself,  but  that  it  seems  to  possess  either 

80  H.  Taine,  De  Intelligence,  8th  ed.,  Vol.  I,  pp.  95  ff.  Paris,  Hachette, 
1897.— A.  Binet,  La  suggestibilite,  pp.  166,  177  f.,  186,  191,  196,  200  etc.  Paris, 
Schleicher,  1900. 

81 E.  Rignano,  "Qu'est-ce  que  la  conscience?"  Scientictj  1907,  Vol.  II,  No. 
IV,  4. 


ATTENTION.  21 

one  or  the  other  of  these  properties  only  when,  having  been 
previously  present,  it  is  now  referred  to  another  psychic 
state  at  present  existing.  And  the  necessary  and  sufficient 
condition  permitting  a  complex  past  psychic  state  to  pre- 
sent itself  again  as  "conscious"  in  relation  to  a  complex 
present  psychic  state  is  that  the  affective  portion  of  the  mne- 
monic evocation  of  the  former  correspond  at  least  in  part 
with  the  coexisting  affective  portion  of  the  latter  and  there- 
fore coalesce  with  it. 

Since,  as  we  have  seen  in  our  frequently  cited  treatise, 
the  possession  of  a  "diffuse  seat"  is  characteristic  of  affec- 
tive tendencies — which  in  this  respect  are  so  different  from 
sensations  and  their  images  whose  seat  is  localized  at  a 
single  point  or  center  and  which  therefore  may  exist  and 
be  active  simultaneously  in  great  numbers  in  one  and  the 
same  brain — it  is  difficult  even  for  only  two  affective  tend- 
encies to  have  their  seats  in  localities  which  shall  not  coin- 
cide more  or  less,  so  that  when  these  tendencies  strive  to 
be  operative  at  the  same  time,  they  either  conflict  with 
each  other,  or  hold  each  other  in  suspense,  or  partially 
coalesce. 

If  the  discharge  of  one  does  not  depend  on  the  dis- 
charge of  the  other,  and  if  the  respective  nervous  activities 
in  the  part  of  their  seats  common  to  both  differ  specifically 
from  each  other,  then  the  activation  of  one  tendency  will 
of  itself  imply  the  exclusion  of  the  other  and  vice  versa.  If 
the  discharge  of  the  one  is  caused  by  the  discharge  of  the 
other  and  the  two  tendencies  are  antagonistic,  we  will  then 
have  the  state  in  which  the  primary  affective  tendency  is 
held  in  suspense  by  the  secondary;  which  condition,  as  we 
have  seen  above,  is  characteristic  of  the  state  of  attention. 
If  on  the  other  hand  the  respective  nervous  activities  in 
that  portion  of  their  seats  common  to  both  are  specifically 
similar,  then  their  blending  together  will  make  the  complex 
psychic  state  to  which  one  of  the  tendencies  belongs  "con- 


22  THE  MONIST. 

scious"  with  reference  to  the  psychic  state  to  which  the 
other  belongs. 

Finally  a  fourth  case  will  occur  but  much  more  rarely 
for  reasons  given  above,  in  which  the  two  affective  tend- 
encies have  no  part  of  their  seats  in  common,  and  accord- 
ingly both  can  be  present  and  operative  at  the  same  time 
without  hindering  each  other  or  bearing  any  relation  what- 
ever to  one  another.  This  case  comprises  all  the  phenom- 
ena of  the  so-called  double  personality.  These  phenomena 
nevertheless  are  by  no  means  always  of  a  pathological 
character,  like  the  typical  ones  studied  especially  by  Janet, 
but  they  may  appear  also  in  normal  persons  in  so-called 
instances  of  absent-mindedness.  Such  was  the  case,  for 
instance,  when  we  were  climbing  down  into  the  valley 
from  Ca'  di  Janzo  by  a  very  steep  mule  path.  Leaping  from 
one  stone  to  another  constantly  demanded  our  whole  at- 
tention in  order  to  measure  exactly  the  distance  of  the 
leap  and  lest  a  foot  should  slip  or  dislodge  a  stone.  Yet 
nevertheless  the  descent  sometimes  proceeded  "uncon- 
sciously" with  reference  to  some  other  very  different  affec- 
tivity  which  produced  at  the  same  time  quite  another  train 
of  thought.22 

In  the  first  case  the  exclusion  of  all  other  tendencies 
with  independent  discharge  as  soon  as  one  of  them  becomes 
active — an  exclusion  which  persists  throughout  the  whole 
time  during  which  the  first  of  the  two  affective  tendencies 
of  the  state  of  attention  remains  "held  in  suspense" — forms 
the  so-called  "unity  of  consciousness." 

In  other  words,  the  impossibility  for  more  than  one  pri- 
mary affective  tendency  to  be  active  at  any  one  time  re- 
sults in  the  impossibility  of  giving  heed  to  more  than  one 
object  at  one  time:  "A  plurality  of  stimulations  of  the 
nerves  may  co-exist,  but  they  affect  the  consciousness  only 

28  P.  Janet,  L'automatisme  psychologique,  pp.  263  ft.  Paris,  Alcan,  1907... 
Taine,  De  I' intelligence,  pp.  16  ff.— Rignano,  Qu'est-ce  que  la  conscience?  pp. 
11-13- 


ATTENTION.  23 

by  turns,  or  one  at  a  time.  The  reason  is  that  the  bodily 
organs  are  collectively  engaged  with  each  distinct  con- 
scious state,  and  they  cannot  be  doing  two  things  at  the 
same  instant/'23 

Consequently  attention  ordinarily  is  never  divided  or 
dispersed.  If  it  is  greatly  roused  it  will  continue  to  be  di- 
rected toward  any  given  objects  for  a  while  and  hence  can 
not  be  directed  to  any  others  during  this  entire  period. 
If  it  is  less  aroused  it  passes  from  one  object  to  another 
in  quick  succession  and  accordingly  seems  to  be  divided 
among  many  objects  at  the  same  time;  but  in  reality  even 
in  this  case  it  is  directed  at  each  moment  to  one  object 
only,  that  is,  to  the  one  which  corresponds  to  the  momen- 
tary affective  tendency.  Accordingly  the  slpeaker  who 
passes  judgment  upon  his  own  speech,  the  actor  who  has 
command  over  himself,  the  chess  player  who  plays  several 
games  at  one  time,  Julius  Csesar  who  dictated  several  let- 
ters at  once,  do  not  prove  the  simultaneous  presence  of 
several  states  of  attention,  but  rather  their  rapid  succession 
and  the  alternating  predominance  of  first  one  and  then  an- 
other.24 

For  this  reason  the  attention  directed  by  self-contempla- 
tion upon  any  affective  state  brings  about  the  end  and 
disappearance  of  that  state.  It  is  impossible  to  direct 
one's  attention  upon  an  affectivity.  If  .the  attempt  is  made 
that  particular  mood  ceases  at  once,  and  we  are  turned 
aside  by  a  compelling  sensation  or  idea  which  we  have  not 
the  slightest  desire  to  observe.25  For  the  attention  which 
is  directed  upon  an  affectivity  within  ourselves  is  a  newly 
originated  affectivity,  namely  the  one  that  impels  us  to 

23  Bain,  The  Emotions  and  the  Will,  p.  5. 

84  E.  Meumann,  Intelligens  und  Wille,  pp.  22  ff.  Leipsic,  Quelle  &  Meyer, 
1908. 

88  E.  B.  Titchener,  The  Psychology  of  Feeling  and  Attention,  p.  69.  New 
York,  Macmillan,  1908. 


24  THE  MONIST. 

this  observation  and  investigation,  and  therefore  it  dis- 
places the  other  we  wished  to  observe. 

Since  the  primary  affective  tendency  of  the  state  of 
attention  excludes  every  other  affectivity  independently 
evoked  and  in  this  way  protects  the  unity  of  our  conscious- 
ness, it  makes  it  possible  at  the  same  time  for  every  past 
state  of  attention  involved  to  appear  conscious  to  us  if  we 
now  think  back  to  it  and  to  the  object  which  at  that  time 
constituted  the  end  desired.  For  this  memory  will  now  be 
recalled  to  the  same  object  by  a  more  or  less  similar  affec- 
tive tendency  which  therefore  will  partially  blend  with  the 
recollection  of  the  former. 

Every  state  of  attention  accordingly  contains  all  ele- 
ments within  itself  in  order  later  to  seem  to  us  to  be  con- 
scious; but  not  all  past  psychic  states  which  now  appear 
conscious  were  states  of  attention,  as  Kohn  maintains  to 
whom  the  state  of  attention  and  the  conscious  state  are 
the  same  thing.  For  an  affectivity  which  becomes  at 
once  completely  active  and  therefore  does  not  give  rise 
to  any  state  of  attention  —  like  a  hurried  flight  caused 
by  sudden  terror — is  nevertheless  able  to  make  the  com- 
plex psychic  state  involved  appear  a  conscious  one.26  In 
other  words,  the  state  of  attention  is  a  sufficient  but  not 
a  necessary  condition  of  consciousness.  The  only  condi- 
tion which  is  at  the  same  time  necessary  and  sufficient  is 
the  presence  of  some  affective  tendency,  no  matter  whether 
it  be  in  the  state  of  suspense  or  of  full  activation. 

The  acts  which  have  become  automatic,  for  instance 
those  which  originated  through  affective  choice  as  con- 
scious movements,  and  which  later  by  means  of  attention 
were  perfected  under  the  affective  conflict  of  the  tendencies 
to  perform  the  act  but  at  the  same  time  to  avoid  one  by 
one  its  many  imperfections,  are  finally  consummated  after 

26  See  H.  E.  Kohn,  Zur  Theorie  der  Aufmerksamkeit,  pp.  19,  27.  Halle, 
Niemeyer,  1895. 


ATTENTION.  25 

frequent  repetition — according  to  the  mnemonic  law  that 
the  part  gradually  becomes  independent  of  the  whole — 
without  requiring  any  "impulsion"  or  any  kind  of  affec- 
tive aid  whatever,  either  primarily  in  the  execution  or 
secondarily  by  way  of  improvement.  For  this  reason  we 
are  accustomed  to  say  that  rendering  acts  automatic  lib- 
erates the  attention  so  that  it  may  be  directed  to  other 
objects.27 

And  just  because  acts  which  have  become  automatic 
do  not  require  attention  on  our  part  and  take  place  without 
the  assistance  of  any  affective  element,  they  always  seem 
to  us  to  be  unconscious.  Consciousness,  as  Maudsley 
says,  directs  the  process  of  adaptation,  the  efforts  to  be- 
come expert  in  adjusting  the  various  means  to  their  proper 
ends  and  the  successive  stages  of  organization;  it  disap- 
pears as  soon  as  the  skill  has  been  thoroughly  attained.28 

"Habit,"  says  James,  "diminishes  the  conscious  atten- 
tion with  which  our  acts  are  performed.  One  may  state 
this  abstractly  thus:  If  an  act  require  for  its  execution  a 
chain  of  successive  nervous  events,  then  in  the  first  per- 
formances of  the  action  the  conscious  will  must  choose 
each  of  these  events  from  a  number  of  wrong  alternatives 
that  tend  to  present  themselves ;  for  consciousness  is  always 
and  chiefly  a  selective  agency.  But  habit  soon  brings  it 
about  that  each  event  calls  up  its  own  appropriate  successor 
without  any  alternative  offering  itself  and  without  any 
reference  to  the  conscious  will,  until  at  last  the  whole  chain 
rattles  itself  off  as  soon  as  the  first  event  occurs,  just  as 
if  this  and  the  rest  of  the  chain  were  fused  into  a  con- 
tinuous stream."29 

Just  as  an  act  that  has  become  automatic  represents  a 
nervous  activity  which  in  the  absence  of  any  accompanying 

"Meumann,  Intelligens  und  Wille,  p.  23. 
88  Maudsley,  The  Pathology  of  Mind,  p.  9. 

29  Win.  James,  The  Principles  of  Psychology,  Vol.  I,  pp.  114,  139.  London, 
Macmillan,  1901.  The  same,  briefer  course,  p.  139.  New  York,  Holt,  1893. 


26  THE  MONIST. 

affective  tendency  remains  unconscious,  so  will  every  stim- 
ulation of  our  senses  remain  unconscious  when  it  reaches 
its  sensory  seat  if  it  can  not  arouse  any  affectivity  in 
us.  On  the  other  hand  every  stimulation  of  our  senses 
which  succeeds  in  discharging  any  one  of  the  many  affec- 
tive tendencies  potentially  present  in  the  brain,  will  after- 
wards appear  conscious  to  us;  and  this  may  also  be  ex- 
pressed by  saying  that  the  "stimulation  has  succeeded  in 
taking  possession  of  the  sensor  him."30  Whence  it  follows 
that  if  all  objective  and  sensitive  peripheral  relations  re- 
main the  same,  it  will  depend  on  whether  our  attention  is 
or  is  not  directed  upon  something  else  and  on  the  degree 
of  strength  and  of  opposition  of  the  primary  affectivity 
involved — for  thence  is  derived  the  power  to  exclude  every 
other  affective  tendency  which  differs  from  it — whether 
certain  stimuli  remain  quite  unobserved  or  whether  they 
will  appear  to  us  as  conscious  sensations.31 

Says  James:  "A  million  things  in  the  outside  world 
are  present  to  my  senses  but  do  not  enter  my  conscious- 
ness. Why?  Because  they  do  not  interest  me.  Only  that 
which  arouses  my  attention  makes  up  my  experience.  Only 
the  objects  to  which  I  give  heed  constitute  my  understand- 
ing. Without  selective  interest  experience  is  a  veritable 
chaos.  Interest  first  gives  color  and  tone  to  the  image, 
light  and  shadow,  background  and  foreground,  in  a  word 
a  distinct  perspective."32 

The  primary  affectivity  of  a  state  of  averted  attention 
may  be  so  strong  that  it  can  prevent  even  the  most  intense 
irritations,  which  at  other  times  would  seem  altogether 
painful  and  arouse  within  us  the  most  strenuous  effort  to 
remove  them,  from  reaching  our  consciousness.  Classical, 

80  G.  E.  Miiller,  Zur  Theorie  dcr  sinnlichen  Aufmerksamkeit,  pp.  77.  Leip- 
sic,  Edelmann. 

8X  Miiller,  op.  cit.}  p.  I. — Kiilpe,  op.  cit.,  p.  40  f. — Ostwald,  Vorlesungen 
ilber  Natur philosophic,  pp.  400  ff. 

83  James,  op.  cit.,  Vol.  I,  p.  402. 


ATTENTION.  27 

for  instance,  is  the  case  of  the  Christian  martyr  whose  en- 
tranced attention  was  to  such  a  degree  absorbed  by  the 
beatific  visions  presented  to  his  eyes,  that  it  prevented  him 
from  feeling  the  pain  of  the  horrible  tortures  to  which  his 
body  was  subjected.  No  less  significant  is  the  case  of 
Robert  Hall,  some  of  whose  "most  eloquent  discourses 
were  poured  forth  whilst  he  was  suffering  under  a  bodily 
disorder  which  caused  him  to  roll  in  agony  on  the  floor 
when  he  descended  from  the  pulpit;  yet  he  was  entirely 
unconscious  of  the  irritation  of  his  nerves  by  the  calculus 
which  shot  forth  its  jagged  points  through  the  whole  sub- 
stance of  his  kidney,  so  long  as  his  soul  continued  to  be 
'possessed'  by  the  great  subjects  upon  which  a  powerful 
effort  of  his  will  originally  fixed  it."33 

However,  a  large  number  of  facts  go  to  prove  that  those 
very  irritations  which  do  not  discharge  any  affectivity  or 
are  not  capable  of  arousing  our  attention  and  therefore 
remain  unconscious,  nevertheless  likewise  succeed  in  reach- 
ing their  sensory  seats.  "The  fact  that  we  sometimes  be- 
come conscious  of  many  sensuous  impressions,  such  as 
for  instance  the  stroke  of  a  bell,  after  the  stimulus  has 
made  itself  felt  in  our  sense-organ,  tends  to  show  that  the 
excitation  reaches  its  destination  rightly  enough,  but  that 
the  sensory  center  happens  at  the  moment  to  be  in  a  state 
not  suited  for  the  reception  of  the  afferent  stimulus."34 

The  conflict  also  between  the  different  states  of  atten- 
tion which  the  varied  stimuli  from  the  outside  world  would 
strive  to  arouse — owing  to  the  fact  that  only  one  single 
primary  affective  tendency  can  ever  be  operative  at  any 
one  moment — indicates  that,  whatever  the  relation  of  the 
stimulations  to  consciousness  may  be,  they  always  reach 
their  habitual  psychical  center;  for  otherwise  they  could 
not  all  tend  to  discharge  their  respective  affectivities. 

88  W.  P.  Carpenter,  Principles  of  Mental  Physiology,  7th  ed.,  p.  138.  London, 
Kegan  Paul,  1896. 

84  Miiller,  Zur  Theorie  der  sinnl.  Aufm.,  p.  105. 


28  THE  MONIST. 

"When  one  of  the  various  stimuli  succeeds  in  the  struggle  to 
obtain  possession  of  consciousness  we  say  that  we  are  atten- 
tive to  it  according  to  the  intensity  of  the  corresponding 
process  of  consciousness."  "But  we  can  not  maintain  that 
excitations  which  do  not  enter  our  consciousness  because 
of  averted  attention  do  not  enter  at  all  into  the  organ  of 
consciousness,  the  cortex  of  the  brain."35 

It  often  happens  in  my  own  case,  for  instance,  that  I 
am  reading  a  newspaper  while  the  other  members  of  the 
family  are  chatting  together  in  the  same  room  or  perhaps 
while  one  of  them  reads  aloud  from  a  book  or  a  different 
paper.  Sometimes  I  do  not  succeed  in  limiting  my  atten- 
tion to  what  I  myself  am  reading  because  my  interest  is 
aroused  by  what  I  hear  read  aloud.  In  other  cases,  how- 
ever, I  succeed  very  well,  and  then  I  no  longer  hear  the 
words  of  those  in  the  room.  Nevertheless  one  word  pro- 
nounced by  the  reader  in  exactly  the  same  tone  as  all  the 
other  words — for  he  is  reading  right  along  in  the  same 
monotonous  voice — suddenly  draws  me  completely  away 
from  what  I  am  reading  and  turns  my  attention  to  what 
he  is  reading  aloud.  Thus  my  attention  vibrates  con- 
stantly back  and  forth  between  what  I  am  reading  and 
what  I  am  hearing  read.  The  fact  of  this  conflict  between 
the  two  states  of  attention  accordingly  proves  most  posi- 
tively, I  repeat,  that  the  irritations  produced  by  the  spoken 
words  of  another  reach  their  sensory  center,  their  sensory 
basis,  in  me  even  in  moments  when  I  am  not  aware  of  them ; 
otherwise  none  of  them  would  be  able  to  rivet  my  interest 
or  attention. 

The  same  is  obviously  true  for  all  so-called  states  of 
absentmindedness  which  at  bottom,  as  we  have  already 
seen,  are  only  the  first  physiological  indications  of  that 
double  state  of  one's  own  personality  which  hitherto  has 

MKohn,  Zur  Theorie  der  Aufm.,  p.  19;  and  Sigmund  Exner,  Entwurf  su 
einer  physiologischen  Erkldrung  der  psychischen  Erscheinungen.  Part  I,  p. 
72.  Vienna  and  Leipsic,  Deuticke,  1894. 


ATTENTION.  29 

been  investigated  almost  exclusively  in  its  pathological 
forms.  As  an  example  of  this  we  mentioned  in  our  essay 
on  consciousness  the  locking  of  a  drawer  while  attention 
was  directed  elsewhere.  This  showed  that  all  stimulations 
of  sight  proceeding  from  the  key-hole  and  the  key  placed 
in  it  reached  their  goal  although  they  remained  entirely 
unconscious.  Every  one  has  the  experience  of  walking 
absentmindedly  through  the  streets  and  yet  without  run- 
ning into  people,  vehicles,  or  any  other  obstructing  objects 
on  the  way.  Our  previously  mentioned  "unconscious" 
descent  from  the  Ca'  di  Janzo  proves  how  perfectly  in 
every  respect  the  perception  of  all  the  difficulties  of  the  way 
must  have  been — the  stones,  their  form,  their  position,  their 
state  of  equilibrium — if  I  were  to  succeed  in  leaping  from 
one  stone  to  another  without  falling  or  knocking  down  a 
stone. 

The  primary  affective  tendency  which  constitutes  that 
state  of  attention  which  is  directed  on  a  definite  object,  by 
no  means  excludes  the  intrusion  of  sensations  which  at  the 
time  have  no  interest ;  or,  in  other  words,  it  does  not  pre- 
vent excitations  of  a  sensory  character  from  reaching  their 
goal,  their  normal  destination,  even  when  we  are  uncon- 
scious of  them ;  but  they  only  oppose  the  affective  tendency 
which  would  endeavor  to  arouse  these  sensations. 

"The  entrance  of  a  stimulus  into  consciousness" — as 
it  is  expressed  by  Kohn  and  others — does  not  rest  upon  the 
possible  intrusion  of  the  stimulus  at  any  particular  part 
of  the  brain  or  sensorium  whose  specific  function  would 
be  that  of  consciousness.  No  more  does  it  depend  upon  a 
single  "center  of  perception"  as  Wundt  assumes.  But  it 
consists  only  in  the  fact  that  this  stimulus  evokes  some  affec- 
tive tendency  relating  to  the  object  which  it  represents. 
When  this  evocation  takes  place  the  stimulus  reaches  con- 
sciousness; if  it  does  not  take  place,  perhaps  because  at 
this  moment  another  affective  tendency  referring  to  other 


3O  THE  MONIST. 

sensations  is  operative,  then,  although  the  stimulus  may 
penetrate  physiologically  to  the  same  point  as  usual,  it  can- 
not reach  consciousness  and  hence  remains  unobserved  and 
unconscious.  The  persistence  of  the  mnemonic  accumula- 
tions of  those  sensations  which  remain  outside  of  con- 
sciousness and  the  possibility  of  evoking  them  again  in 
the  future  are  at  a  great  disadvantage  from  the  cir- 
cumstance that  they  are  not  able  to  excite  any  affective 
state  peculiar  to  themselves  with  which  they  could  be  con- 
nected or  associated. 

Having  thus  elucidated  the  inmost  nature  of  the  affec- 
tive conflict  peculiar  to  attention  in  its  main  points,  and 
having  seen  wherein  consists  that  unity  of  consciousness 
which  so  many  inquirers  declare  to  be  one  of  its  most  es- 
sential fundamental  properties,  space  does  not  now  permit 
us  to  pass  on  to  the  study  of  the  effects  arising  from  this 
inmost  nature  and  fundamental  property  of  attention  upon 
sensations  and  ideas,  as  in  general  for  the  whole  process 
of  intelligence. 

E.    RlGNANO. 

MILAN,  ITALY. 


CHANCE.1 

T  T  OW  dare  we  speak  of  the  laws  of  chance?  Is  not 
JTl  chance  the  antithesis  of  all  law?"  So  says  Ber- 
trand  at  the  beginning  of  his  Calcul  des  probability.  Prob- 
ability is  opposed  to  certitude ;  so  it  is  what  we  do  not  know 
and  consequently  it  seems  what  we  could  not  calculate. 
Here  is  at  least  apparently  a  contradiction,  and  about  it 
much  has  already  been  written. 

And  first,  what  is  chance  ?  The  ancients  distinguished 
between  phenomena  seemingly  obeying  harmonious  laws, 
established  once  for  all,  and  those  which  they  attributed 
to  chance;  these  were  the  ones  unpredictable  because  re- 
bellious to  all  law.  In  each  domain  the  precise  laws  did  not 
decide  everything,  they  only  drew  limits  between  which 
chance  might  act.  In  this  conception  the  word  chance  had 
a  precise  and  objective  meaning :  what  was  chance  for  one 
was  also  chance  for  another  and  even  for  the  gods. 

But  this  conception  is  not  ours  to-day.  We  have  be- 
come absolute  determinists,  and  even  those  who  want  to 
reserve  the  rights  of  human  free  will  let  determinism  reign 
undividedly  in  the  inorganic  world  at  least.  Every  phe- 
nomenon, however  minute,  has  a  cause;  and  a  mind  in- 
finitely powerful,  infinitely  well-informed  about  the  laws 
of  nature,  could  have  foreseen  it  from  the  beginning  of  the 
centuries.  If  such  a  mind  existed,  we  could  not  play  with 
it  at  any  game  of  chance,  we  should  always  lose. 

In  fact  for  it  the  word  chance  would  not  have  any  mean- 

1  Translated  by  G.  B.  Halsted. 


32  THE  MONIST. 

ing,  or  rather  there  would  be  no  chance.  It  is  because  of 
our  weakness  and  our  ignorance  that  the  word  has  a  mean- 
ing for  us.  And,  even  without  going  beyond  our  feeble 
humanity,  what  is  chance  for  the  ignorant,  is  not  chance 
for  the  scientist.  Chance  is  only  the  measure  of  our  ig- 
norance. Fortuitous  phenomena  are,  by  definition,  those 
whose  laws  we  do  not  know. 

But  is  this  definition  altogether  satisfactory?  When 
the  first  Chaldean  shepherds  followed  with  their  eyes  the 
movements  of  the  stars,  they  knew  not  as  yet  the  laws  of 
astronomy;  would  they  have  dreamed  of  saying  that  the 
stars  move  at  random?  If  a  modern  physicist  studies  a 
new  phenomenon,  and  if  he  discovers  its  law  Tuesday, 
would  he  have  said  Monday  that  this  phenomenon  was 
fortuitous  ?  Moreover,  do  we  not  often  invoke  what  Ber- 
trand  calls  the  laws  of  chance,  to  predict  a  phenomenon? 
For  example  in  the  kinetic  theory  of  gases  we  obtain  the 
known  laws  of  Mariotte  and  of  Gay-Lussac  by  means  of 
the  hypothesis  that  the  velocities  of  the  molecules  of  gas 
vary  irregularly,  that  is  to  say  at  random.  All  physicists 
will  agree  that  the  observable  laws  would  be  much  less 
simple  if  the  velocities  were  ruled  by  any  simple  elemen- 
tary law  whatsoever,  if  the  molecules  were,  as  we  say, 
organised,  if  they  were  subject  to  some  discipline.  It  is 
due  to  chance,  that  is  to  say  to  our  ignorance,  that  we  can 
draw  our  conclusions;  and  then  if  the  word  chance  is 
simply  synonymous  with  ignorance  what  does  that  mean? 
Must  we  therefore  translate  it  as  follows? 

"You  ask  me  to  predict  for  you  the  phenomena  about  to 
happen.  If,  unluckily,  I  knew  the  laws  of  these  phe- 
nomena I  could  make  the  prediction  only  by  inextricable 
calculations  and  would  have  to.  renounce  attempting  to 
answer  you ;  but  as  I  may  chance  not  to  know,  I  will  answer 
you  at  once.  And  what  is  most  surprising,  my  answer 
will  be  right." 


CHANCE.  33 

So  it  must  well  be  that  chance  is  something  other  than 
the  name  we  give  our  ignorance,  that  among  phenomena 
whose  causes  are  unknown  to  us  we  must  distinguish  for- 
tuitous phenomena  about  which  the  calculus  of  probabil- 
ities will  provisionally  give  information,  from  those  which 
are  not  fortuitous  and  of  which  we  can  say  nothing  so  long 
as  we  shall  not  have  determined  the  laws  governing  them. 
For  the  fortuitous  phenomena  themselves,  it  is  clear  that 
the  information  given  us  by  the  calculus  of  probabilities 
will  not  cease  to  be  true  upon  the  day  when  these  phenom- 
ena shall  be  better  known. 

The  director  of  a  life  insurance  company  does  not  know 
when  each  of  the  insured  will  die,  but  he  relies  upon  the 
calculus  of  probabilities  and  on  the  law  of  great  numbers 
and  he  is  not  deceived  since  he  distributes  dividends  to  his 
stockholders.  These  dividends  would  not  vanish  if  a  very 
penetrating  and  very  indiscrete  physician  should,  after  the 
policies  were  signed,  reveal  to  the  director  the  life  chances 
of  the  insured.  This  doctor  would  dissipate  the  ignorance 
of  the  director,  but  he  would  have  no  influence  on  the  divi- 
dends which  evidently  are  not  an  outcome  of  this  ignorance. 

*  #  * 

To  find  a  better  definition  of  chance  we  must  examine 
some  of  the  facts  which  we  agree  to  regard  as  fortuitous, 
and  to  which  the  calculus  of  probabilities  seems  to  apply; 
we  then  shall  investigate  what  are  their  common  char- 
acteristics. 

The  first  example  we  select  is  that  of  unstable  equi- 
librium; if  a  cone  rests  upon  its  apex,  we  know  well  that 
it  will  fall,  but  we  do  not  know  toward  what  side;  it  seems 
to  us  chance  alone  will  decide.  If  the  cone  were  perfectly 
symmetric,  if  its  axis  were  perfectly  vertical,  if  it  were 
acted  upon  by  no  force  other  than  gravity,  it  would  not 
fall  at  all.  But  the  least  defect  in  symmetry  will  make  it 
lean  slightly  toward  one  side  or  the  other,  and  if  it  leans, 


34  THE  MONIST. 

however  little,  it  will  fall  altogether  toward  that  side.  Even 
if  the  symmetry  were  perfect,  a  very  slight  tremor,  a  breath 
of  air  could  make  it  incline  some  seconds  of  arc;  this  will 
be  enough  to  determine  its  fall  and  even  the  sense  of  its 
fall  which  will  be  that  of  the  initial  inclination. 

A  very  slight  cause,  which  escapes  us,  determines  a 
considerable  effect  which  we  cannot  help  seeing,  and  then 
we  say  this  effect  is  due  to  chance.  If  we  could  know 
exactly  the  laws  of  nature  and  the  situation  of  the  universe 
at  the  initial  instant,  we  should  be  able  to  predict  exactly 
the  situation  of  this  same  universe  at  a  subsequent  instant. 
But  even  then  when  the  natural  laws  should  have  no  fur- 
ther secret  for  us,  we  could  know  the  initial  situation  only 
approximately.  If  that  permits  us  to  foresee  the  subse- 
quent situation  with  the  same  degree  of  approximation, 
this  is  all  we  require,  we  say  the  phenomenon  has  been  pre- 
dicted, that  it  is  ruled  by  laws ;  but  it  is  not  always  so.  It 
may  happen  that  slight  differences  in  the  initial  conditions 
produce  very  great  differences  in  the  final  phenomena;  a 
slight  error  in  the  former  would  make  an  enormous  error 
in  the  latter.  Prediction  becomes  impossible  and  we  have 
the  fortuitous  phenomenon. 

Our  second  example  will  be  very  analogous  to  the  first 
and  we  shall  take  it  from  meteorology.  Why  have  the 
meteorologists  such  difficulty  in  predicting  the  weather 
with  any  certainty  ?  Why  do  the  rains,  the  tempests  them- 
selves seem  to  us  to  come  by  chance,  so  that  many  persons 
find  it  quite  natural  to  pray  for  rain  or  shine,  when  they 
would  think  it  ridiculous  to  pray  for  an  eclipse?  We  see 
that  great  perturbations  generally  happen  in  regions  where 
the  atmosphere  is  in  unstable  equilibrium.  The  meteorol- 
ogists are  aware  that  this  equilibrium  is  unstable,  that  a 
cyclone  is  arising  somewhere;  but  where  they  cannot  tell; 
one-tenth  of  a  degree  more  or  less  at  any  point,  and  the 
cyclone  bursts  here  and  not  there,  and  spreads  its  ravages 


CHANCE.  35 

over  countries  it  would  have  spared.  This  we  could  have 
foreseen  if  we  had  known  that  tenth  of  a  degree,  but  the 
observations  were  neither  sufficiently  close  nor  sufficiently 
precise,  and  for  this  reason  all  seems  due  to  the  agency  of 
chance.  Here  again  we  find  the  same  contrast  between  a 
very  slight  cause,  unappreciable  to  the  observer,  and  im- 
portant effects,  which  are  sometimes  tremendous  disasters. 

Let  us  pass  to  another  example,  the  distribution  of  the 
minor  planets  on  the  zodiac.  Their  initial  longitudes  can 
have  been  any  longitudes  whatever;  but  their  mean  mo- 
tions were  different  and  they  have  revolved  for  so  long 
a  time  that  we  may  say  they  are  now  distributed  at  random 
along  the  zodiac.  Very  slight  initial  differences  between 
their  distances  from  the  sun,  or,  what  comes  to  the  same 
thing,  between  their  mean  motions,  have  ended  by  giving 
enormous  differences  between  their  present  longitudes.  An 
excess  of  the  thousandth  of  a  second  in  the  daily  mean 
motion  will  give  in  fact  a  second  in  three  years,  a  degree  in 
ten  thousand  years,  an  entire  circumference  in  three  or 
four  million  years,  and  what  is  that  to  the  time  which  has 
passed  since  the  minor  planets  have  detached  themselves 
from  the  nebula  of  Laplace?  Again  therefore  we  see  a 
slight  cause  and  a  great  effect ;  or  better,  slight  differences 
in  the  cause  and  great  differences  in  the  effect. 

The  game  of  roulette  does  not  take  us  as  far  as  might 
seem  from  the  preceding  example.  Assume  a  needle  to 
be  turned  on  a  pivot  over  a  dial  divided  into  a  hundred 
sectors  alternately  red  and  black.  If  it  stops  on  a  red  sector 
I  win,  if  not,  I  lose.  Evidently  all  depends  upon  the  initial 
impulse  I  give  the  needle.  The  needle  will  make,  suppose, 
ten  or  twenty  turns,  but  it  will  stop  sooner  or  not  so  soon 
according  as  I  shall  have  pushed  it  more  or  less  strongly. 
It  suffices  that  the  impulse  vary  only  by  a  thousandth  or 
a  two  thousandth  to  make  the  needle  stop  over  a  black 
sector  or  over  the  following  red  one.  These  are  differences 


36  THE  MONIST. 

the  muscular  sense  cannot  distinguish  and  which  elude 
even  the  most  delicate  instruments.  So  it  is  impossible  for 
me  to  foresee  what  the  needle  I  have  started  will  do,  and 
this  is  why  my  heart  throbs  and  I  hope  everything  from 
luck.  The  difference  in  the  cause  is  imperceptible,  and  the 
difference  in  the  effect  is  for  me  of  the  highest  importance, 

since  it  means  my  whole  stake. 

#       *       * 

Permit  me,  in  this  connection,  a  thought  somewhat 
foreign  to  my  subject.  Some  years  ago  a  philosopher  said 
that  the  future  is  determined  by  the  past,  but  not  the  past 
by  the  future;  or,  in  other  words,  from  knowledge  of 
the  present  we  could  deduce  the  future,  but  not  the  past; 
because,  said  he,  a  cause  can  have  only  one  effect,  while  the 
same  effect  might  be  produced  by  several  different  causes. 
It  is  clear  no  scientist  can  subscribe  to  this  conclusion. 
The  laws  of  nature  bind  the  antecedent  to  the  consequent 
in  such  a  way  that  the  antecedent  is  as  well  determined 
by  the  consequent  as  the  consequent  by  the  antecedent. 
But  whence  came  the  error  of  this  philosopher  ?  We  know 
that  in  virtue  of  Carnot's  principle  physical  phenomena  are 
irreversible  and  the  world  tends  toward  uniformity.  When 
two  bodies  of  different  temperature  come  in  contact,  the 
warmer  gives  up  heat  to  the  colder ;  so  we  may  foresee  that 
the  temperature  will  equalize.  But  once  equal,  if  asked 
about  the  anterior  state,  what  can  we  answer?  We  might 
say  that  one  was  warm  and  the  other  cold,  but  not  be 
able  to  divine  which  formerly  was  the  warmer. 

And  yet  in  reality  the  temperatures  will  never  reach 
perfect  equality.  The  differences  of  temperature  only  tend 
asymptotically  toward  zero.  There  comes  a  moment  when 
our  thermometers  are  powerless  to  make  it  known.  But 
if  we  had  thermometers  a  thousand  times,  a  hundred  thou- 
sand times  as  sensitive,  we  should  recognize  that  there  still 
is  a  slight  difference,  and  that  one  of  the  bodies  remains 


CHANCE.  37 

a  little  warmer  than  the  other,  and  so  we  could  say  this 
it  is  which  formerly  was  much  the  warmer. 

So  then  there  are,  contrary  to  what  we  found  in  the 
former  examples,  great  differences  in  cause  and  slight 
differences  in  effect.  Flammarion  once  imagined  an  ob- 
server going  away  from  the  earth  with  a  velocity  greater 
than  that  of  light ;  for  him  time  would  have  changed  sign. 
History  would  be  turned  about,  and  Waterloo  would  pre- 
cede Austerlitz.  Well,  for  this  observer,  effects  and  causes 
would  be  inverted;  unstable  equilibrium  would  no  longer 
be  the  exception.  Because  of  the  universal  irreversibility 
all  would  seem  to  him  to  come  out  of  a  sort  of  chaos  in 
unstable  equilibrium.  All  nature  would  appear  to  him  de- 
livered over  to  chance. 

*       *       * 

Now  for  other  examples  where  we  shall  see  somewhat 
different  characteristics.  Take  first  the  kinetic  theory  of 
gases.  How  should  we  picture  a  receptacle  filled  with  gas  ? 
Innumerable  molecules,  moving  at  high  speeds,  flash 
through  this  receptacle  in  every  direction.  At  every  in- 
stant they  strike  against  its  walls  or  each  other,  and  these 
collisions  happen  under  the  most  diverse  conditions.  What 
above  all  impresses  us  here,  is  not  the  littleness  of  the 
causes,  but  their  complexity,  and  yet  the  former  element 
is  still  found  here  and  plays  an  important  role.  If  a  mol- 
ecule deviated  right  or  left  from  its  trajectory,  by  a  very 
small  quantity,  comparable  to  the  radius  of  action  of  the 
gaseous  molecules,  it  would  avoid  a  collision  or  sustain  it 
under  different  conditions,  and  that  would  vary  the  direc- 
tion of  its  velocity  after  the  impact,  perhaps  by  ninety  de- 
grees or  by  a  hundred  and  eighty  degrees. 

And  this  is  not  all ;  we  have  just  seen  that  it  is  necessary 
to  deflect  the  molecule  before  the  clash  by  only  an  infini- 
tesimal, to  produce  its  deviation  after  the  collision  by  a 
finite  quantity.  If  then  the  molecule  undergoes  two  sue- 


38  THE  MONIST. 

cessive  shocks,  it  will  suffice  to  deflect  it  before  the  first  by 
an  infinitesimal  of  the  second  order,  for  it  to  deviate  after 
the  first  encounter  by  an  infinitesimal  of  the  first  order, 
and  after  the  second  hit,  by  a  finite  quantity.  And  the 
molecule  will  not  undergo  merely  two  shocks;  it  will 
undergo  a  very  great  number  per  second.  So  that  if  the 
first  shock  has  multiplied  the  deviation  by  a  very  large 
number  A,  after  n  shocks  it  will  be  multiplied  by  An.  It 
will  therefore  become  very  great  not  merely  because  A  is 
large,  that  is  to  say  because  little  causes  produce  big  effects, 
but  because  the  exponent  n  is  large,  that  is  to  say  because 
the  shocks  are  very  numerous  and  the  causes  very  complex. 

Take  a  second  example.  Why  do  the  drops  of  rain  in 
a  shower  seem  to  be  distributed  at  random  ?  This  is  again 
because  of  the  complexity  of  the  causes  which  determine 
their  formation.  Ions  are  distributed  in  the  atmosphere. 
For  a  long  while  they  have  been  subjected  to  air-currents 
constantly  changing,  they  have  been  caught  in  very  small 
whirlwinds,  so  that  thetr  final  distribution  has  no  longer 
any  relation  to  their  initial  distribution.  Suddenly  the 
temperature  falls,  vapor  condenses,  and  each  of  these  ions 
becomes  the  center  of  a  drop  of  rain.  To  know  what  will 
be  the  distribution  of  these  drops  and  how  many  will  fall 
on  each  paving-stone,  it  would  not  be  sufficient  to  know  the 
initial  situation  of  the  ions,  it  would  be  necessary  to  com- 
pute the  effect  of  a  thousand  little  capricious  air-currents. 

And  again  it  is  the  same  if  we  put  grains  of  powder  in 
suspension  in  water.  The  vase  is  ploughed  by  the  currents 
whose  law  we  know  not,  we  only  know  it  is  very  compli- 
cated. At  the  end  of  a  certain  time  the  grains  will  be  dis- 
tributed at  random,  that  is  to  say  uniformly,  in  the  vase; 
and  this  is  due  precisely  to  the  complexity  of  these  currents. 
If  they  obeyed  some  simple  law,  if  for  example  the  vase  re- 
volved and  the  currents  circulated  around  the  axis  of  the 
vase,  describing  circles,  it  would  no  longer  be  the  same, 


CHANCE.  39 

since  each  grain  would  retain  its  initial  altitude  and  its 
initial  distance  from  the  axis. 

We  should  reach  the  same  result  in  considering  the 
mixing  of  two  liquids  or  of  two  fine-grained  powders.  And 
to  take  a  grosser  example,  this  is  also  what  happens  when 
we  shuffle  playing-cards.  At  each  stroke,  the  cards  un- 
dergo a  permutation  (analogous  to  that  studied  in  the 
theory  of  substitutions).  What  will  happen?  The  prob- 
ability of  a  particular  permutation  (for  example  that  bring- 
ing to  the  nth  place  the  card  occupying  the  4>OHh  place 
before  the  permutation)  depends  upon  the  player's  habits. 
But  if  this  player  shuffles  the  cards  long  enough,  there  will 
be  a  great  number  of  successive  permutations,  and  the 
resulting  final  order  will  no  longer  be  governed  by  aught 
but  chance;  I  mean  to  say  that  all  possible  orders  will  be 
equally  probable.  It  is  to  the  great  number  of  successive 
permutations,  that  is  to  say  to  the  complexity  of  the  phe- 
nomenon, that  this  result  is  due. 

A  final  word  about  the  theory  of  errors.  Here  it  is 
that  the  causes  are  complex  and  multiple.  To  how  many 
snares  is  not  the  observer  exposed,  even  with  the  best  in- 
strument! He  should  apply  himself  to  finding  out  the 
largest  and  avoiding  them.  These  are  the  ones  giving 
birth  to  systematic  errors.  But  when  he  has  eliminated 
those,  admitting  that  he  succeeds,  there  remain  many  small 
ones  which,  their  effects  accumulating,  may  become  dan- 
gerous. Thence  come  the  accidental  errors;  and  we  at- 
tribute them  to  chance  because  their  causes  are  too  com- 
plicated and  too  numerous.  Here  again  we  have  only  little 
causes  each  of  which  might  produce  only  a  slight  effect; 
it  is  by  their  union  and  their  number  that  their  effects  be- 
came formidable. 

*       *       * 

We  may  take  still  a  third  point  of  view,  less  important 
than  the  first  two  and  upon  which  I  shall  lay  less  stress. 


4<D  THE   MONIST. 

When  we  seek  to  foresee  an  event  and  examine  its  antece- 
dents, we  strive  to  search  into  the  anterior  situation.  This 
could  not  be  done  for  all  parts  of  the  universe  and  we  are 
content  to  know  what  is  passing  in  the  neighborhood  of 
the  point  where  the  event  should  occur,  or  what  would 
appear  to  have  some  relation  to  it.  An  examination  can- 
not be  complete  and  we  must  know  how  to  choose.  But  it 
may  happen  that  we  have  passed  by  circumstances  which 
at  first  sight  seemed  completely  foreign  to  the  foreseen  hap- 
pening, to  which  one  would  never  have  dreamed  of  attrib- 
uting any  influence  and  which  nevertheless,  contrary  to 
all  anticipation,  come  to  play  an  important  role. 

A  man  passes  in  the  street  going  to  his  business ;  some 
one  knowing  the  business  could  have  told  why  he  started 
at  such  a  time  and  went  by  such  a  street.  On  the  roof 
works  a  tiler.  The  contractor  employing  him  could  in  a 
certain  measure  foresee  what  he  would  do.  But  the 
passer-by  scarcely  thinks  of  the  tiler,  nor  the  tiler  of  him ; 
they  seem  to  belong  to  two  worlds  completely  foreign  to 
one  another.  And  yet  the  tiler  drops  a  tile  which  kills  the 
man,  and  we  do  not  hesitate  to  say  this  is  chance. 

Our  weakness  forbids  our  considering  the  entire  uni- 
verse and  makes  us  cut  it  up  into  slices.  We  try  to  do 
this  as  little  artificially  as  possible.  And  yet  it  happens 
from  time  to  time  that  two  of  these  slices  react  upon  one 
another.  The  effects  of  this  mutual  action  then  seem  to  us 
to  be  due  to  chance. 

Is  this  a  third  way  of  conceiving  chance?  Not  always; 
in  fact  most  often  we  are  carried  back  to  the  first  or  the 
second.  Whenever  two  worlds  usually  foreign  to  one  an- 
other, come  thus  to  react  upon  each  other,  the  laws  of  this 
reaction  must  be  very  complex.  On  the  other  hand  a  very 
slight  change  in  the  initial  conditions  of  these  two  worlds 
would  have  been  sufficient  for  the  reaction  not  to  have 


CHANCE.  41 

happened.     How  little  was  needed  for  the  man  to  pass  a 

second  later  or  the  tiler  to  drop  his  tile  a  second  sooner. 

*       *       * 

All  we  have  said  still  does  not  explain  why  chance  obeys 
laws.  Does  the  fact  that  the  causes  are  slight  or  complex 
suffice  for  our  foreseeing,  if  not  their  effects  in  each  case, 
at  least  what  their  effects  will  be,  on  the  average?  To  an- 
swer this  question  we  had  better  take  up  again  some  of 
the  examples  already  cited. 

I  shall  begin  with  that  of  the  roulette.  I  have  said  that 
the  point  where  the  needle  will  stop  depends  upon  the  initial 
push  given  it.  What  is  the  probability  of  this  push  having 
this  or  that  value  ?  I  know  nothing  about  it,  but  it  is  diffi- 
cult for  me  not  to  suppose  that  this  probability  is  repre- 
sented by  a  continuous  analytic  function.  The  probability 
that  the  push  is  comprised  between  «  and  a+c  will  then  be 
sensibly  equal  to  the  probability  of  its  being  comprised 
between  <*+*  and  «+2e,  provided  «  be  very  small.  This  is 
a  property  common  to  all  analytic  functions.  Minute  vari- 
ations of  the  function  are  proportional  to  minute  variations 
of  the  variable. 

But  we  have  assumed  that  an  exceedingly  slight  variation 
of  the  push  suffices  to  change  the  color  of  the  sector  over 
which  the  needle  finally  stops.  From  <*  to  a+c  it  is  red, 
from  a+e  to  a+2«  it  is  black;  the  probability  of  each  red 
sector  is  therefore  the  same  as  of  the  following  black,  and 
consequently  the  total  probability  of  red  equals  the  total 
probability  of  black. 

The  datum  of  the  question  is  the  analytic  function  rep- 
resenting the  probability  of  a  particular  initial  push.  But 
the  theorem  remains  true  whatever  be  this  datum,  since  it 
depends  upon  a  property  common  to  all  analytic  functions. 
From  this  it  follows  finally  that  we  no  longer  need  the 
datum. 

What  we  have  just  said  for  the  case  of  the  roulette 


42  THE  MONIST. 

applies  also  to  the  example  of  the  minor  planets.  The  zo- 
diac may  be  regarded  as  an  immense  roulette  on  which  have 
been  tossed  many  little  balls  with  different  initial  impulses 
varying  according  to  some  law.  Their  present  distribution 
is  uniform  and  independent  of  this  law,  for  the  same  rea- 
son as  in  the  preceding  case.  Thus  we  see  why  phenomena 
obey  the  laws  of  chance  when  slight  differences  in  the 
causes  suffice  to  bring  on  great  differences  in  the  effects. 
The  probabilities  of  these  slight  differences  may  then  be 
regarded  as  proportional  to  these  differences  themselves, 
just  because  these  differences  are  minute,  and  the  infini- 
tesimal increments  of  a  continuous  function  are  propor- 
tional to  those  of  the  variable. 

Take  an  entirely  different  example,  where  intervenes 
especially  the  complexity  of  the  causes.  Suppose  a  player 
shuffles  a  pack  of  cards.  At  each  shuffle  he  changes  the 
order  of  the  cards,  and  he  may  change  them  in  many  ways. 
To  simplify  the  exposition,  consider  only  three  cards.  The 
cards  which  before  the  shuffle  occupied  respectively  the 
places  123,  may  after  the  shuffle  occupy  the  places 

123,  231,  312,  321,  132,  213. 

Each  of  these  six  hypotheses  is  possible  and  they  have  re- 
spectively for  probabilities: 

pi,  fa,  ps,  p±,  p*>  PQ. 

The  sum  of  these  six  numbers  equals  I ;  but  this  is  all 
we  know  of  them ;  these  six  probabilities  depend  naturally 
upon  the  habits  of  the  player  which  we  do  not  know. 

At  the  second  shuffle  and  the  following,  this  will  recom- 
mence, and  under  the  same  conditions ;  I  mean  that  p±  for 
example  represents  always  the  probability  that  the  three 
cards  which  occupied  after  the  nth  shufflle  and  before  the 
n-(-ith  the  places  123,  occupy  the  places  321  after  the 
n+ith  shuffle.  And  this  remains  true  whatever  be  the 
number  n,  since  the  habits  of  the  player  and  his  way  of 
shuffling  remain  the  same. 


CHANCE.  43 

But  if  the  number  of  shuffles  is  very  great,  the  cards 
which  before  the  first  shuffle  occupied  the  places  123  may, 
after  the  last  shuffle,  occupy  the  places 

123,  231,  312,  321,  132,  213 

and  the  probability  of  these  six  hypotheses  will  be  sensibly 
the  same  and  equal  to  1/6;  and  this  will  be  true  whatever 
be  the  numbers  pi .  . .  .  pQ  which  we  do  not  know.  The  great 
number  of  shuffles,  that  is  to  say  the  complexity  of  the 
causes,  has  produced  uniformity. 

This  wrould  apply  without  change  if  there  were  more 
than  three  cards,  but  even  with  three  cards  the  demon- 
stration would  be  complicated;  let  it  suffice  to  give  it  for 
only  two  cards.  Then  we  have  only  two  possibilities  12, 
21  with  the  probabilities  pi  and  p2  =  i — pi. 

Suppose  n  shuffles  and  suppose  I  win  one  franc  if  the 
cards  are  finally  in  the  initial  order  and  lose  one  if  they 
are  finally  inverted.  Then,  my  mathematical  expectation 
will  be  (pi—p2)n. 

The  difference  pi — p2  is  certainly  less  than  i ;  so  that 
if  n  is  very  great  my  expectation  will  be  zero ;  we  need  not 
learn  pi  and  p2  to  be  aware  that  the  game  is  equitable. 

There  would  always  be  an  exception  if  one  of  the  num- 
bers pi  and  p2  was  equal  to  i  and  the  other  naught.  Then 
it  would  not  apply  because  our  initial  hypotheses  would  be 
too  simple. 

What  we  have  just  seen  applies  not  only  to  the  mixing 
of  cards  but  to  all  mixings,  to  those  of  powders  and  of 
liquids ;  and  even  to  those  of  the  molecules  of  gases  in  the 
kinetic  theory  of  gases. 

To  return  to  this  theory,  suppose  for  a  moment  a  gas 
whose  molecules  cannot  mutually  clash,  but  may  be  devi- 
ated by  hitting  the  insides  of  the  vase  wherein  the  gas  is 
confined.  If  the  form  of  the  vase  is  sufficiently  complex 
the  distribution  of  the  molecules  and  that  of  the  velocities 
will  not  be  long  in  becoming  uniform.  But  this  will  not 


44  THE  MONIST. 

be  so  if  the  vase  is  spherical  or  if  it  has  the  shape  of  a 
cuboid.  Why  ?  Because  in  the  first  case  the  distance  from 
the  center  to  any  trajectory  will  remain  constant;  in  the 
second  case  this  will  be  the  absolute  value  of  the  angle  of 
each  trajectory  with  the  faces  of  the  cuboid. 

So  we  see  what  should  be  understood  by  conditions  too 
simple]  they  are  such  as  conserve  something,  which  leave 
an  invariant  remaining.  Are  the  differential  equations  of 
the  problem  too  simple  for  us  to  apply  the  laws  of  chance? 
This  question  would  seem  at  first  view  to  lack  precise 
meaning;  now  we  know  what  it  means.  They  are  too 
simple  if  they  conserve  something,  if  they  admit  a  uniform 
integral.  If  something  in  the  initial  conditions  remains 
unchanged,  it  is  clear  the  final  situation  can  no  longer  be 
independent  of  the  initial  situation. 

We  come  finally  to  the  theory  of  errors.  We  know 
not  to  what  are  due  the  accidental  errors,  and  precisely 
because  we  do  not  know  we  are  aware  they  obey  the 
law  of  Gauss.  Such  is  the  paradox.  The  explanation 
is  nearly  the  same  as  in  the  preceding  cases.  We  need 
know  only  one  thing:  that  the  errors  are  very  numer- 
ous, that  they  are  very  slight,  that  each  may  be  as  well 
negative  as  positive.  What  is  the  curve  of  probability  of 
each  of  them?  We  do  not  know;  we  only  suppose  it  is 
symmetric.  We  prove  then  that  the  resultant  error  will 
follow  Gauss's  law,  and  this  resulting  law  is  independent 
of  the  particular  laws  which  we  do  not  know.  Here  again 
the  simplicity  of  the  result  is  born  of  the  very  complexity 

of  the  data. 

*       *       * 

But  we  are  not  through  with  paradoxes.  I  have  just 
recalled  the  figment  of  Flammarion,  that  of  the  man  going 
quicker  than  light,  for  whom  time  changes  sign.  I  said 
that  for  him  all  phenomena  would  seem  due  to  chance. 
That  is  true  from  a  certain  point  of  view,  and  yet  all  these 


CHANCE.  45 

phenomena  at  a  given  moment  would  not  be  distributed  in 
conformity  with  the  laws  of  chance  since  the  distribution 
would  be  the  same  as  for  us,  who  seeing  them  unfold  har- 
moniously and  without  coming  out  of  a  primal  chaos,  do 
not  regard  them  as  ruled  by  chance. 

What  does  that  mean  ?  For  Lumen,  Flammarion's  man, 
slight  causes  seem  to  produce  great  effects;  why  do  not 
things  go  on  as  for  us  when  we  think  we  see  grand  effects 
due  to  little  causes?  Would  not  the  same  reasoning  be 
applicable  in  his  case? 

Let  us  return  to  the  argument.  When  slight  differences 
in  the  causes  produce  vast  differences  in  the  effects,  why 
are  these  effects  distributed  according  to  the  laws  of 
chance?  Suppose  a  difference  of  a  millimeter  in  the  cause 
produces  a  difference  of  a  kilometer  in  the  effect.  If  I 
win  in  case  the  effect  corresponds  to  a  kilometer  bearing 
an  even  number,  my  probability  of  winning  will  be  1/2. 
Why?  Because  to  make  that,  the  cause  must  correspond 
to  a  millimeter  with  an  even  number.  Now,  according  to 
all  appearance,  the  probability  of  the  cause  varying  be- 
tween certain  limits  will  be  proportional  to  the  distance 
apart  of  these  limits,  provided  this  distance  be  very  small. 
If  this  hypothesis  were  not  admitted  there  would  no  longer 
be  any  way  of  representing  the  probability  by  a  continuous 
function. 

What  now  will  happen  when  great  causes  produce 
small  effects?  This  is  the  case  where  we  should  not  at- 
tribute the  phenomenon  to  chance  and  where  on  the  con- 
trary Lumen  would  attribute  it  to  chance.  To  a  difference 
of  a  kilometer  in  the  cause  would  correspond  a  difference 
of  a  millimeter  in  the  effect.  Would  the  probability  of  the 
cause  being  comprised  between  two  limits  n  kilometers 
apart  still  be  proportional  to  n?  We  have  no  reason  to 
suppose  so,  since  this  distance,  n  kilometers,  is  great.  But 
the  probability  that  the  effect  lies  between  two  limits  n 


46  THE  MONIST. 

millimeters  apart  will  be  precisely  the  same,  so  it  will  not 
be  proportional  to  n,  even  though  this  distance,  n  milli- 
meters, be  small.  There  is  no  way  therefore  of  represent- 
ing the  law  of  probability  of  effects  by  a  continuous  curve. 
This  curve,  understand,  may  remain  continuous  in  the 
analytic  sense  of  the  word;  to  infinitesimal  variations  of 
the  abscissa  will  correspond  infinitesimal  variations  of  the 
ordinate.  But  practically  it  will  not  be  continuous,  since 
very  small  variations  of  the  ordinate  would  not  correspond 
to  very  small  variations  of  the  abscissa.  It  would  become 
impossible  to  trace  the  curve  with  an  ordinary  pencil ;  that 
is  what  I  mean. 

So  what  must  we  conclude?  Lumen  has  no  right  to 
say  that  the  probability  of  the  cause  (his  cause,  our  effect) 
should  be  represented  necessarily  by  a  continuous  func- 
tion. But  then  why  have  we  this  right  ?  It  is  because  this 
state  of  unstable  equilibrium  which  we  have  been  calling 
initial  is  itself  only  the  final  outcome  of  a  long  previous 
history.  In  the  course  of  this  history  complex  causes  have 
worked  a  great  while:  they  have  contributed  to  produce 
the  mixture  of  elements  and  they  have  tended  to  make 
everything  uniform  at  least  within  a  small  region;  they 
have  rounded  off  the  corners,  smoothed  down  the  hills  and 
filled  up  the  valleys.  However  capricious  and  irregular 
may  have  been  the  primitive  curve  given  over  to  them, 
they  have  worked  so  much  toward  making  it  regular  that 
finally  they  deliver  over  to  us  a  continuous  curve.  And 
this  is  why  we  may  in  all  confidence  assume  its  continuity. 

Lumen  would  not  have  the  same  reasons  for  such  a 
conclusion.  For  him  complex  causes  would  not  seem 
agents  of  equalization  and  regularity,  but  on  the  con- 
trary would  create  only  inequality  and  differentiation.  He 
would  see  a  world  more  and  more  varied  come  forth  from 
a  sort  of  primitive  chaos.  The  changes  he  could  observe 
would  be  for  him  unforeseen  and  impossible  to  foresee. 


CHANCE.  47 

They  would  seem  to  him  due  to  some  caprice  or  another ; 
but  this  caprice  would  be  quite  different  from  our  chance, 
since  it  would  be  opposed  to  all  law,  while  our  chance  still 
has  its  laws.  All  these  points  call  for  lengthy  explications 
which  perhaps  would  aid  in  the  better  comprehension  of 

the  irreversibility  of  the  universe. 

#       *       * 

We  have  sought  to  define  chance,  and  now  it  is  proper 
to  put  a  question.  Has  chance  thus  defined,  in  so  far  as 
this  is  possible,  objectivity? 

It  may  be  questioned.  I  have  spoken  of  very  slight  or 
very  complex  causes.  But  what  is  very  little  for  one  may 
be  very  big  for  another,  and  what  seems  very  complex  to 
one  may  seem  simple  to  another.  In  part  I  have  already 
answered  by  saying  precisely  in  what  cases  differential 
equations  become  too  simple  for  the  laws  of  chance  to  re- 
main applicable.  But  it  is  fitting  to  examine  the  matter  a 
little  more  closely,  because  we  may  take  still  other  points 
of  view. 

What  means  the  phrase  "very  slight"  ?  To  understand 
it  we  need  only  go  back  to  what  has  already  been  said.  A 
difference  is  very  slight,  an  interval  is  very  small,  when 
within  the  limits  of  this  interval  the  probability  remains 
sensibly  constant.  And  why  may  this  probability  be  re- 
garded as  constant  within  a  small  interval  ?  It  is  because 
we  assume  that  the  law  of  probability  is  represented  by  a 
continuous  curve,  continuous  not  only  in  the  analytic  sense 
but  practically  continuous,  as  already  explained.  This 
means  that  it  not  only  presents  no  absolute  hiatus  but  that 
it  has  neither  salients  nor  reentrants  too  acute  or  too  ac- 
centuated. 

And  what  gives  us  the  right  to  make  this  hypothesis? 
We  have  already  said  it  is  because,  since  the  beginning  of 
the  ages,  there  have  always  been  complex  causes  cease- 
lessly acting  in  the  same  way  and  making  the  world  tend 


48  THE  MONIST. 

toward  uniformity  without  ever  being  able  to  turn  back. 
These  are  the  causes  which  little  by  little  have  flattened 
the  salients  and  filled  up  the  reentrants  and  this  is  why 
our  probability  curves  now  show  only  gentle  undulations. 
In  milliards  of  milliards  of  ages  another  step  will  have 
been  made  toward  uniformity,  and  these  undulations  will 
be  ten  times  as  gentle;  the  radius  of  mean  curvature  of 
our  curve  will  have  become  ten  times  as  great.  And  then 
such  a  length  as  seems  to  us  to-day  not  very  small,  since 
on  our  curve  an  arc  of  this  length  cannot  be  regarded  as 
rectilineal,  should  on  the  contrary  at  that  epoch  be  called 
very  little,  since  the  curvature  will  have  become  ten  times 
less  and  an  arc  of  this  length  may  be  sensibly  identified 
with  a  sect. 

Thus  the  phrase  "very  slight"  remains  relative;  but 
it  is  not  relative  to  such  or  such  a  man,  it  is  relative  to  the 
actual  state  of  the  world.  It  will  change  its  meaning  when 
the  world  shall  have  become  more  uniform,  when  all  things 
shall  have  blended  still  more.  But  then  doubtless  men 
can  no  longer  live  and  must  give  place  to  other  beings- 
should  I  say  far  smaller  or  far  larger  ?  So  that  our  crite- 
rion, remaining  true  for  all  men,  retains  an  objective  sense. 

And  on  the  other  hand  what  means  the  phrase  "very 
complex"?  I  have  already  given  one  solution,  but  there 
are  others.  Complex  causes  we  have  said  produce  a  blend 
more  and  more  intimate,  but  after  how  long  a  time  will 
this  blend  satisfy  us?  When  will  it  have  accumulated 
sufficient  complexity?  When  shall  we  have  sufficiently 
shuffled  the  cards?  If  we  mix  two  powders,  one  blue  the 
other  white,  there  comes  a  moment  when  the  tint  of  the 
mixture  seems  to  us  uniform  because  of  the  feebleness  of 
our  senses;  it  will  be  uniform  for  the  presbyte,  forced  to 
gaze  from  afar,  before  it  will  be  so  for  the  myope.  And 
when  it  has  become  uniform  for  all  eyes,  we  still  could 
push  back  the  limit  by  the  use  of  instruments.  There  is 


CHANCE.  49 

no  chance  for  any  man  ever  to  discern  the  infinite  variety 
which,  if  the  kinetic  theory  is  true,  hides  under  the  uniform 
appearance  of  a  gas.  And  yet  if  we  accept  Gouy's  ideas 
on  the  Brownian  movement,  does  not  the  microscope  seem 
on  the  point  of  showing  us  something  analogous? 

This  new  criterion  is  therefore  relative  like  the  first; 
and  if  it  retains  an  objective  character,  it  is  because  all 
men  have  approximately  the  same  senses,  the  power  of 
their  instruments  is  limited,  and  besides  they  use  it  only 

exceptionally. 

*       *       * 

It  is  just  the  same  in  the  moral  sciences  and  particu- 
larly in  history.  The  historian  is  obliged  to  make  a  choice 
among  the  events  of  the  epoch  he  studies ;  he  recounts  only 
those  which  seem  to  him  the  most  important.  He  therefore 
contents  himself  with  relating  the  most  momentous  events 
of  the  sixteenth  century  for  example,  as  likewise  the  most 
remarkable  facts  of  the  seventeenth  century.  If  the  first 
suffice  to  explain  the  second,  we  say  these  conform  to  the 
laws  of  history.  But  if  a  great  event  of  the  seventeenth 
century  should  have  for  cause  a  small  fact  of  the  sixteenth 
century  which  no  history  reports,  which  all  the  world  has 
neglected,  then  we  say  this  event  is  due  to  chance.  This 
word  has  therefore  the  same  sense  as  in  the  physical  sci- 
ences; it  means  that  slight  causes  have  produced  great 
effects. 

The  greatest  bit  of  chance  is  the  birth  of  a  great  man. 
It  is  only  by  chance  that  meeting  of  two  germinal  cells, 
of  different  sex,  containing  precisely,  each  on  its  side,  the 
mysterious  elements  whose  mutual  reaction  must  produce 
the  genius.  One  will  agree  that  these  elements  must  be 
rare  and  that  their  meeting  is  still  more  rare.  How  slight 
a  thing  it  would  have  required  to  deflect  from  its  route  the 
carrying  spermatozoon.  It  would  have  sufficed  to  deflect 
it  a  tenth  of  a  millimeter  and  Napoleon  would  not  have 


50  THE  MONIST. 

been  born  and  the  destinies  of  a  continent  would  have  been 
changed.  No  example  can  better  make  us  understand  the 
veritable  characteristics  of  chance. 

One  more  word  about  the  paradoxes  brought  out  by  the 
application  of  the  calculus  of  probabilities  to  the  moral 
sciences.  It  has  been  proved  that  no  Chamber  of  Deputies 
will  ever  fail  to  contain  a  member  of  the  opposition,  or  at 
least  such  an  event  would  be  so  improbable  that  we  might 
without  fear  wager  the  contrary,  and  bet  a  million  against 
a  sou. 

Condorcet  has  striven  to  calculate  how  many  jurors  it 
would  require  to  make  a  judicial  error  practically  impos- 
sible. If  we  had  used  the  results  of  this  calculation,  we 
should  certainly  have  been  exposed  to  the  same  disappoint- 
ments as  in  betting,  on  the  faith  of  the  calculus,  that  the 
opposition  would  never  be  without  a  representative. 

The  laws  of  chance  do  not  apply  to  these  questions.  If 
justice  be  not  always  meted  out  to  accord  with  the  best 
reasons,  it  uses  less  than  we  think  the  method  of  Bridoye. 
This  is  perhaps  to  be  regretted,  for  then  the  system  of  Con- 
dorcet would  shield  us  from  judicial  errors. 

What  is  the  meaning  of  this?  We  are  tempted  to  at- 
tribute facts  of  this  nature  to  chance  because  their  causes 
are  obscure;  but  this  is  not  true  chance.  The  causes  are 
unknown  to  us  it  is  true,  and  they  are  even  complex;  but 
they  are  not  sufficiently  so,  since  they  conserve  something. 
We  have  seen  that  this  it  is  which  distinguishes  causes 
"too  simple."  When  men  are  brought  together  they  no 
longer  decide  at  random  and  independently  one  of  another ; 
they  influence  one  another.  Multiplex  causes  come  into 
action.  They  worry  men,  dragging  them  to  right  or  left, 
but  one  thing  there  is  they  cannot  destroy,  this  is  their 

Panurge  flock-of-sheep  habits.    And  this  is  an  invariant. 

*       #       # 

Difficulties  are  indeed  involved  in  the  application  of  the 


CHANCE.  SI 

calculus  of  probabilities  to  the  exact  sciences.  Why  are 
the  decimals  of  a  table  of  logarithms,  why  are  those  of  the 
number  w  distributed  in  accordance  with  the  laws  of  chance  ? 
Elsewhere  I  have  already  studied  the  question  in  so  far  as 
it  concerns  logarithms,  and  there  it  is  easy.  It  is  clear 
that  a  slight  difference  of  argument  will  give  a  slight 
difference  of  logarithm,  but  a  great  difference  in  the  sixth 
decimal  of  the  logarithm.  Always  we  find  again  the  same 
criterion. 

But  as  for  the  number  T,  that  presents  more  difficulties, 
and  I  have  at  the  moment  nothing  worth  while  to  say. 

There  would  be  many  other  questions  to  resolve,  had  I 
wished  to  attack  them  before  solving  that  which  I  more 
specially  set  myself.  When  we  reach  a  simple  result,  when 
we  find  for  example  a  round  number,  we  say  that  such  a 
result  cannot  be  due  to  chance,  and  we  seek,  for  its  explana- 
tion, a  non-fortuitous  cause.  And  in  fact  there  is  only  a 
very  slight  probability  that  among  10,000  numbers  chance 
will  give  a  round  number,  for  example  the  number  10,000. 
This  has  only  one  chance  in  10,000.  But  there  is  only  one 
chance  in  10,000  for  the  occurrence  of  any  other  one  num- 
ber ;  and  yet  this  result  will  not  astonish  us,  nor  will  it  be 
hard  for  us  to  attribute  it  to  chance ;  and  that  simply  be- 
cause it  will  be  less  striking. 

Is  this  a  simple  illusion  of  ours,  or  are  there  cases 
where  this  way  of  thinking  is  legitimate?  We  must  hope 
so,  else  were  all  science  impossible.  When  we  wish  to 
check  a  hypothesis,  what  do  we  do?  We  cannot  verify 
all  its  consequences,  since  they  would  be  infinite  in  num- 
ber ;  we  content  ourselves  with  verifying  certain  ones  and 
if  we  succeed  we  declare  the  hypothesis  confirmed,  because 
so  much  success  could  not  be  due  to  chance.  And  this  is 
always  at  bottom  the  same  reasoning. 

I  cannot  completely  justify  it  here,  since  it  would  take 
too  much  time;  but  I  may  at  least  say  that  we  find  our- 


52  THE  MONIST. 

selves  confronted  by  two  hypotheses,  either  a  simple  cause 
or  that  aggregate  of  complex  causes  we  call  chance.  We 
find  it  natural  to  suppose  that  the  first  should  produce  a 
simple  result,  and  then,  if  we  find  that  simple  result,  the 
round  number  for  example,  it  seems  more  likely  to  us  to  be 
attributable  to  the  simple  cause  which  must  give  it  almost 
certainly,  than  to  chance  which  could  only  give  it  once  in 
10,000  times.  It  will  not  be  the  same  if  we  find  a  result 
which  is  not  simple;  chance,  it  is  true,  will  not  give  this 
more  than  once  in  10,000  times;  but  neither  has  the  simple 
cause  any  more  chance  of  producing  it. 

HENRI  POINCARE. 
PARIS,  FRANCE. 


THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS.* 


QUARES  like  those  shown  in  Figs,  i  and  2,  in  which 
the  numbers  occur  in  their  natural  order,  are  known 
as  natural  squares.  In  such  squares,  it  will  be  noticed  that 
the  numbers  in  associated1  cells  are  complementary,  i.  e., 
their  sum  is  twice  the  mean  number.  It  follows  that  any 
two  columns  equally  distant  from  the  central  bar  of  the 
lattice  are  complementary  columns,  that  is,  the  magic  sum 


1 

2 

3 

4 

5 

6 

7 

8 

9 

10 

11 

12 

13 

14 

15 

16 

1 

2 

3 

4 

5 

6 

7 

8 

9 

10 

11 

12 

13 

14 

IS 

16 

17 

18 

19 

20 

21 

22 

23 

24 

25 

26 

27 

28 

29 

30 

31 

32 

33 

34 

35 

36 

Fig.  i. 


Fig.  2. 


will  be  the  mean  of  their  sums.  Further  any  two  numbers 
in  these  complementary  columns  which  lie  in  the  same 
row  have  a  constant  difference,  and  therefore  the  sums  of 
the  two  columns  differ  by  n  times  this  difference.  If  then 
we  raise  the  lighter  column  and  depress  the  heavier  col- 
umn by  11/2  times  this  difference  we  shall  bring  both  to  the 

*This  paper  was  extracted  about  18  months  ago  from  three  different 
parts  of  an  unpublished  treatise  written  in  1894.  With  regard  to  footnote 
6,  p.  63,  since  this  was  written  Sayles  and  Worthington  have  independently 
solved  the  problem  of  construction  for  63. 

*Two  cells  are  said  to  be  associated  when  the  straight  line  joining  their 
centers  intersects  the  center  of  the  lattice,  and  they  are  equally  distant  from 
that  center. 


54  THE  MONIST. 

mean  value.  Now  we  can  effect  this  change  by  interchang- 
ing half  the  numbers  in  the  one  column  with  the  numbers 
in  the  other  column  lying  in  their  respective  rows.  The 
same  is  true  with  regard  to  rows,  so  that  if  we  can  make 
n/2  horizontal  interchanges  between  every  pair  of  comple- 
mentary columns  and  the  same  number  of  vertical  inter- 
changes between  every  pair  of  complementary  rows,  we 
shall  have  the  magic  sum  in  all  rows  and  columns.  It  is 
easy  to  see  that  we  can  do  this  by  reversing  half  the  rows 
and  half  the  columns,  provided  the  two  operations  are  so 
arranged  as  not  to  interfere  with  one  another.  This  last 
condition  can  be  assured  by  always  turning  over  columns 
and  rows  in  associated  pairs,  for  then  we  shall  have  made 
horizontal  interchanges  only  between  pairs  of  numbers 
previously  untouched  or  between  pairs,  each  of  whose  con- 
stituents has  already  received  an  equal  vertical  displace- 
ment; and  similarly  with  the  vertical  interchanges.  By 
this  method,  it  will  be  noticed,  we  always  secure  magic 
central  diagonals,  for  however  we  choose  our  rows  and 
columns  we  only  alter  the  central  diagonals  of  the  natural 
square  (which  are  already  magic)  by  interchanging  pairs 
of  complementaries  with  other  pairs  of  complementaries. 

Since  the  n/2  columns  have  to  be  arranged  in  pairs  on 
either  side  of  the  central  vertical  bar  of  the  lattice,  n/2  must 
be  even,  and  so  the  method,  in  its  simplest  form,  applies  only 
to  orders  EEEO  (mod  4).  We  may  formulate  the  rule  thus: 
For  orders  of  form  4m,  reverse  m  pairs  of  complementary 
columns  and  m  pairs  of  complementary  rows,  and  the  crude 
magic  is  completed. 

In  the  following  example  the  curved  lines  indicate  the 
rows  and  columns  which  have  been  reversed  (Fig.  3). 

We  have  said  that  this  method  applies  only  when  n/2 
is  even,  but  we  shall  now  show  that  by  a  slight  modification 
it  can  be  applied  to  all  even  orders.  For  suppose  n  is 
double-of-odd ;  we  cannot  then  arrange  half  the  columns 


THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS. 


55 


in  pairs  about  the  center  since  their  number  is  odd,  but 
we  can  so  arrange  n/2 — i  rows  and  n/2 — i  columns,  and 
if  we  reverse  all  these  rows  and  columns  we  shall  have 
made  n/2 — i  interchanges  between  every  pair  of  comple- 
mentary rows  and  columns.  We  now  require  only  to  make 
the  one  further  interchange  between  every  pair  of  rows 
and  columns,  without  interfering  with  the  previous  changes 
or  with  the  central  diagonals.  To  effect  this  is  always 


1 

58 

59 

4 

5 

62 

63 

8 

( 

16 

55 

54 

Id 

12 

51 

50 

9 

c 

17 

42 

43 

20 

21 

46 

47 

24 

32 

39 

38 

29 

28 

35 

34 

25 

40 

31 

30 

37 

36 

27 

26 

33 

41 

18 

19 

44 

45 

22 

23 

48 

c 

56 

15 

14 

53 

52 

11 

10 

49 

57 

2 

3 

60 

61 

6 

7 

64 

Fig.  3- 

easy  with  any  orders  ^2  (mod  4),  (6,  10,  14  etc.),  ex- 
cepting the  first.  In  the  case  of  62  an  artifice  is  necessary. 
If  we  reverse  the  two  central  diagonals  of  a  square  it  will 
be  found,  on  examination,  that  this  is  equivalent  to  re- 
versing two  rows  and  two  columns;  in  fact,  this  gives  us 
a  method  of  forming  the  magic  42  from  the  natural  square 
with  the  least  number  of  displacements,  thus : 


16 

2 

3 

13 

5 

11 

10 

8 

9 

7 

6 

12 

4 

14 

15 

1 

Fig.  4. 


Applying  this  idea,  we  can  complete  the  crude  magic 


THE  MONIST. 


62  from  the  scheme  shown  in  Fig.  5,  where  horizontal  lines 
indicate  horizontal  interchanges,  and  vertical  lines  vertical 
interchanges;  the  lines  through  the  diagonals  implying 
that  the  diagonals  are  to  be  reversed.  The  resulting  magic 
is  shown  in  Fig.  6. 

The  general  method  here  described  is  known  as  the 
method  of  reversions,  and  the  artifice  used  in  the  double- 
of-odd  orders  is  called  the  broken  reversion.  The  method 
of  reversions,  as  applied  to  all  even  orders,  both  in  squares 
and  cubes,  was  first  (  ?)  investigated  by  the  late  W.  Firth, 
Scholar  of  Emmanuel,  Cambridge.2 

The  broken  reversion  for  &  may,  of  course,  be  made  in 
various  ways,  but  the  above  scheme  is  one  of  the  most  sym- 


36 

32 

3 

4 

5 

31 

12 

29 

9 

28 

26 

7 

13 

14 

22 

21 

17 

24 

19 

23 

16 

15 

20 

18 

25 

11 

27 

10 

8 

30 

6 

2 

34 

33 

35 

1 

Fig.  6. 

metrical,  and  may  be  memorialized  thus:  For  horizontal 
changes  commence  at  the  two  middle  cells  of  the  bottom 
row,  and  progress  upwards  and  divergently  along  two 
knight's  paths.  For  vertical  changes  turn  the  square  on 
one  of  its  sides  and  proceed  as  before. 

In  dealing  with  larger  double-of-odd  orders  we  may 
leave  the  central  diagonals  "intact"  and  invert  n/2 — I  rows 
and  n/2 — I  columns.  The  broken  reversion  can  then  al- 
ways be  effected  in  a  multitude  of  ways.  It  must  be  kept 
in  mind,  however,  that  in  making  horizontal  changes  we 
must  not  touch  numbers  which  have  been  already  moved 
horizontally,  and  if  we  use  a  number  which  has  received 

8  Died  1889.    For  historical  notice  vide  section  on  cubes. 


THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS. 


57 


a  vertical  displacement  we  can  only  change  it  with  a  num- 
ber which  has  received  an  equal  vertical  displacement,  and 
similarly  with  vertical  interchanges.  Lastly  we  must  not 
touch  the  central  diagonals. 

Fig.  7  is  such  a  scheme  for  io2,  with  the  four  central 
rows  and  columns  reversed,  and  Fig.  8  shows  the  com- 
pleted magic. 

It  is  unnecessary  to  formulate  a  rule  for  making  the 
reversions  in  these  cases,  because  we  are  about  to  consider 
the  method  from  a  broader  standpoint  which  will  lead  up 
to  a  general  rule. 


1 

92 

8 

94 

95 

96 

97 

3 

9 

10 

20 

12 

13 

84 

85 

86 

87 

88 

19 

11 

71 

29 

23 

74 

75 

76 

77 

28 

22 

30 

40 

39 

38 

67 

66 

65 

64 

33 

62 

31 

50 

49 

48 

57 

56 

55 

54 

43 

42 

51 

60 

59 

58 

47 

46 

45 

44 

53 

52 

41 

70 

69 

68 

37 

36 

35 

34 

63 

32 

61 

21 

72 

73 

24 

25 

26 

27 

78 

79 

80 

81 

82 

83 

17 

15 

16 

14 

18 

89 

90 

91 

2 

93 

4 

6 

5 

7 

98 

99 

100 

Fig.  7- 


Fig.  8. 


If  the  reader  will  consider  the  method  used  in  forming 
the  magic  &  by  reversing  the  central  diagonals,  he  will 
find  that  this  artifice  amounts  to  taking  in  every  column 
two  numbers  equally  distant  from  the  central  horizontal 
bar  and  interchanging  each  of  them  with  its  complemen- 
tary in  the  associated  cell,  the  operation  being  so  arranged 
that  two  and  only  two  numbers  are  moved  in  each  row. 
This,  as  we  have  already  pointed  out,  is  equivalent  to  re- 
versing two  rows  and  two  columns.  Now  these  skew  inter- 
changes need  not  be  made  on  the  central  diagonals — they 
can  be  made  in  any  part  of  the  lattice,  provided  the  con- 


THE  MONIST. 


ditions  just  laid  down  are  attended  to.  If  then  we  make  a 
second  series  of  skew  changes  of  like  kind,  we  shall  have, 
in  effect,  reversed  4  rows  and  4  columns,  and  so  on,  each 
complete  skew  reversion  representing  two  rows  and  col- 
umns. Now  if  n  =  2  (mod  4)  we  have  to  reverse  n/2 — i 
rows  and  colunms  before  making  the  broken  reversion, 
therefore  the  same  result  is  attained  by  making  (n — 2)/4 
complete  sets  of  skew  reversions  and  one  broken  reversion. 

abed 


Fig.  9- 

In  like  manner,  if  n  =  o  (mod  4),  instead  of  reversing  n/2 
rows  and  columns  we  need  only  to  make  n/4  sets  of  skew 
reversions. 

We  shall  define  the  symbol  IX]  as  implying  that  skew 
interchanges  are  to  be  made  between  opposed  pairs  of  the 
four  numbers  symmetrically  situated  with  regard  to  the 
central  horizontal  and  vertical  bars,  one  of  which  numbers 


36 

5 

33 

4 

2 

31 

25 

29 

10 

9 

26 

12 

18 

20 

22 

21 

17 

13 

19 

14 

16 

15 

23 

24 

7 

11 

27 

28 

8 

30 

6 

32 

3 

34 

35 

1 

Fig.  10. 


Fig.  ii. 


Fig.  12. 


occupies  the  cell  in  which  the  symbol  is  placed.  In  other 
words  we  shall  assume  that  Fig.  ga  indicates  what  we  have 
hitherto  represented  as  in  Fig.  gb.  Further,  it  is  quite 
unnecessary  to  use  two  symbols  for  a  vertical  or  horizontal 
change,  for  Fig.  Qc  sufficiently  indicates  the  same  as  Fig. 
gd.  If  these  abbreviations  are  granted,  a  scheme  like  Fig. 


THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS.  59 

5  may  be  replaced  by  a  small  square  like  Fig.  10,  which  is 
to  be  applied  to  the  top  left-hand  corner  of  the  natural  62. 

Fig.  ii  is  the  extended  scheme  from  Fig.  10,  and  Fig. 
12  is  the  resulting  magic.  The  small  squares  of  symbols 
like  Fig.  10  may  be  called  "index  squares" 

The  law  of  formation  for  index  squares  is  sufficiently 
obvious.  To  secure  magic  rows  and  columns  in  the  re- 
sulting square,  the  symbols  —  and  must  occur  once  on 
each  row  and  column  of  the  index,  and  the  symbol  X  an 
equal  number  of  times  on  each  row  and  column;  that  is, 
if  there  are  two  series  X  X  ....  X  the  symbol  X  must  ap- 
pear twice  in  every  row  and  twice  in  every  column,  and 
so  on.  But  we  already  know  by  the  theory  of  paths  that 
these  conditions  can  be  assured  by  laying  the  successive 
symbolic  periods  along  parallel  paths  of  the  index,  whose 
coordinates  are  prime  to  the  order  of  the  index.  If  we 
decide  always  to  use  parallel  diagonal  paths  and  always 
to  apply  the  index  to  the  top  left-hand  corner  of  the  nat- 
ural square,  the  index  square  will  be  completely  represented 
by  its  top  row.  In  Fig.  10  this  is  |X|~~1 1 1 ,  which  we  may  call 
the  index-rod  of  the  square,  or  we  may  simply  call  Fig.  12 
the  magic  |x|-|  H.  Remembering  that  we  require  (n — 2)/4 
sets  of  skew  reversions  when  n  =  2  (mod  4)  and  n/4  when 
n  =  o,  it  is  obvious  that  the  following  rule  will  give  crude 
magic  squares  of  any  even  order  n : 

Take  a  rod  of  n/2  cells,  n/4  symbols  of  the  form  X, 
(using  the  integral  part  of  n/4  only),  and  if  there  is  a  re- 
mainder when  n  is  divided  by  4,  add  the  symbols  |  and  — . 
Place  one  of  the  symbols  X  in  the  left-hand  cell  of  the  rod, 
and  the  other  symbols  in  any  cell,  but  not  more  than  one 
in  each  cell.  The  result  is  an  index-rod  for  the  magic  n2. 

Take  a  square  lattice  of  order  n/2,  and  lay  the  rod  along 
the  top  row  of  the  lattice.  Fill  up  every  diagonal  slant- 
ing downward  and  to  the  right  which  has  a  symbol  in 
its  highest  cell  with  repetitions  of  that  symbol.  The  re- 


6o 


THE  MONIST. 


suiting  index-square  if  applied  to  the  lop  left-hand  corner 
of  the  natural  n2,  with  the  symbols  allowed  the  operative 
powers  already  defined,  will  produce  the  magic  n2. 

The  following  are  index-rods  for  squares  of  even  or- 
ders: 


I02   |x|    jilxH 
122   |x|    I   ixlxl   I 


14^   IxHxl   I   ixjil 

When  the  number  of  cells  in  the  rod  exceeds  the  num- 
ber of  symbols,  as  it  always  does  excepting  with  &,  the  first 
cell  may  be  left  blank.  Also,  if  there  are  sufficient  blank 
cells,  a  X  may  be  replaced  by  two  vertical  and  two  hori- 
zontal symbols.  Thus  I22  might  be  given  so  |x|  1 1 1  |-|xH 


144 

134 

135 

9 

140 

7 

6 

137 

4 

10 

11 

133 

24 

131 

123 

124 

20 

127 

126 

17 

21 

22 

122 

13 

120 

35 

118 

112 

113 

31 

30 

32 

33 

111 

26 

109 

48 

107 

46 

105 

101 

102 

43 

44 

100 

39 

98 

37 

85 

59 

94 

57 

92 

90 

55 

89 

52 

87 

50 

60 

73 

74 

70 

81 

68 

79 

78 

65 

76 

63 

71 

72 

61 

62 

75 

69 

77 

67 

66 

80 

64 

82 

83 

84 

49 

86 

58 

88 

56 

54 

91 

53 

93 

51 

95 

96 

97 

47 

99 

45 

41 

42 

103 

104 

40 

106 

38 

108 

36 

110 

34 

28 

29 

114 

115 

116 

117 

27 

119 

25 

121 

23 

15 

16 

125 

19 

18 

128 

129 

130 

14 

132 

12 

2 

3 

136 

8 

138 

139 

5 

141 

142 

143 

1 

Fig.  13. 


Fig.  14. 


This  presentation  of  I22  is  shown  in  Figs.  13,  14,  and  I42 
from  the  index-rod  given  above,  in  Figs.  15,  16. 

Of  course  the  employment  of  diagonal  paths  in  the  con- 
struction of  the  index  is  purely  a  matter  of  convenience. 
In  the  following  index  for  IO2,  (Fig.  17)  the  skew-symbols 


THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS. 


61 


are  placed  along  two  parallel  paths  (2,  i)  and  the  symbols 
—  and  |  are  then  added  so  that  each  shall  appear  once  in 
each  row  and  once  in  each  column,  but  neither  of  them  on 
the  diagonal  of  the  index  slanting  upward  and  to  the  left. 


196 

13 

194 

4 

5 

191 

189 

8 

188 

10 

11 

185 

2 

183 

169 

181 

26 

179 

19 

20 

176 

175 

23 

24 

172 

17 

170 

28 

168 

156 

166 

39 

164 

34 

35 

36 

37 

159 

32 

157 

41 

155 

43 

153 

143 

151 

52 

149 

49 

50 

146 

47 

144 

54 

142 

56 

57 

58 

138 

130 

136 

65 

134 

133 

62 

131 

67 

129 

69 

70 

126 

72 

73 

123 

117 

121 

78 

77 

118 

80 

116 

82 

83 

113 

98 

111 

87 

88 

108 

104 

106 

105 

93 

103 

95 

96 

100 

85 

99 

97 

101 

102 

94 

90 

92 

91 

107 

89 

109 

110 

86 

112 

84 

114 

115 

81 

75 

79 

119 

120 

76 

122 

74 

124 

125 

71 

127 

128 

68 

60 

66 

132 

64 

63 

135 

61 

137 

59 

139 

140 

141 

55 

45 

53 

145 

51 

147 

148 

48 

150 

46 

152 

44 

154 

42 

30 

40 

158 

38 

160 

161 

162 

163 

33 

165 

31 

167 

29 

15 

27 

171 

25 

173 

174 

22 

21 

177 

178 

18 

180 

16 

182 

14 

184 

12 

186 

187 

9 

7 

190 

6 

192 

193 

3 

195 

1 

Fig.  15- 


Fig.  16. 


Crude  cubes  of  even  orders  we  shall  treat  by  the  index- 
rod  as  in  the  section  on  squares.  The  reader  will  remember 
that  we  constructed  squares  of  orders  =  o  (mod  4)  by  re- 


Fig.  17. 

versing  half  the  rows  and  half  the  columns,  and  it  is  easy 
to  obtain  an  analogous  method  for  the  cubes  of  the  same 
family.  Suppose  we  reverse  half  the  V-planes3  in  asso- 

8  P-plane  =  Presentation-,  or  Paper-plane ;  H-plane  =  Horizontal  plane ; 
V-plane  =  Vertical  plane. 


62 


THE  MONIST. 


ciated  pairs;  that  is,  turn  each  through  an  angle  of  180° 
round  a  horizontal  axis  parallel  to  the  paper-plane  so  that 
the  associated  columns  in  each  plane  are  interchanged  and 
reversed.  We  evidently  give  to  every  row  of  the  cube  the 
magic  sum,  for  half  the  numbers  in  each  row  will  be  ex- 


1 

62 

63 

4 

5 

58 

59 

8 

9 

54 

55 

12 

13 

50 

51 

16 

33 

30 

31 

36 

37 

26 

27 

40 

41 

22 

23 

44 

45 

18 

19 

48 

1 

62 

63 

4 

56 

11 

10 

53 

60 

7 

6 

57 

13 

50 

51 

16 

33 

30 

31 

36 

24 

43 

42 

21 

28 

39 

38 

25 

45 

18 

19 

48 

Magic  in  rows  and  columns. 
Fig.  19.    Being  Fig.  18  with  H-planes  reversed. 


1 

62 

63 

4 

56 

11 

10 

53 

60 

7 

6 

57 

13 

50 

51 

16 

32 

35 

34 

29 

41 

22 

23 

44 

37 

26 

27 

40 

20 

47 

46 

17 

48 

19 

18 

45 

25 

38 

39 

28 

21 

42 

43 

24 

36 

31 

30 

33 

Magic  in  rows,  columns  and  lines. 
Fig.  20.    Being  Fig.  19,  with  P-planes  reversed. 

CRUDE  MAGIC  43. 

changed  for  their  complementaries.  If  we  do  likewise 
with  H-planes  and  P-planes  the  rows  and  lines4  will  become 
magic.  But  as  with  the  square,  and  for  like  reasons,  these 
three  operations  can  be  performed  without  mutual  inter- 
ference. Hence  the  simple  general  rule  for  all  cubes  of  the 
double-of-even  orders : 

*"Lme"  =  a  contiguous  series  of  cells  measured  at  right  angles  to  the 
paper-plane. 


THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS. 


Reverse,  in  associated  pairs,  half  the  V -planes,  half  the 
H-planes,  and  half  the  P-planes. 

With  this  method  the  central  great  diagonals,  of  course, 
maintain  their  magic  properties,  as  they  must  do  for  the 
cube  to  be  considered  even  a  crude  magic.5  To  make  the 
operation  clear  to  the  reader  we  append  views  of  43  at  each 

ABC 


6'74 


7' 


46 


6'47 


2e35 


47'6 


45'8 


'7 


46 


'7 


64 


2538 


53 


82 


47 


" 


28 


83S2 


.X 


" 


58 


2538 


V 

3 


s35a 


Fig.  21. 

separate  stage,  the  central  pair  of  planes  being  used  at 
each  reversion. 

By  this  method  the  reader  can  make  any  crude  magic 
cube  of  order  qm.  With  orders  of  form  4^+2  we  find 
the  same  difficulties  as  with  squares  of  like  orders.  So 
far  as  we  are  aware  no  magic  cube  of  this  family  had  been 


15 

19 

8 

7 

14 

21 

20 

9 

13 

26 

6 

10 

12 

25 

5 

4 

11 

27 

Fig.  22. 

constructed  until  Firth  succeeded  with  63  in  1889,  and  we 
believe  those  we  shall  presently  construct  are  the  first 
which  have  been  published.6  Firth's  original  cube  was 
built  up  by  the  method  of  "pseudo-cubes,"  being  an  exten- 
sion to  solid  magics  of  Thompson's  method.  The  cube  of 
216  cells  was  divided  into  27  subsidiary  cubes  each  con- 

5  A  cube  which  is  faulty  on  one  of  its  central  great  diagonals  is  no  more  a 
magic  than  is  a  square  which  is  faulty  on  one  of  its  central  diagonals. 

6  The  recent  examples  published  by  Willis  and  Kingery  fail  in  their  central 
great  diagonals,  a  fatal  defect. 


64 


THE  MONIST. 


taining  2  cells  in  an  edge.  The  8  cells  of  each  subsidiary 
were  filled  with  the  numbers  I  to  8  in  such  a  way  that  each 
row,  column,  line,  and  central  great  diagonal  of  the  large 
cube  summed  27.  The  cube  was  then  completed  by  using 
the  magic  33  in  the  same  way  that  62  is  constructed  from 
32.  Firth  formulated  no  rule  for  arrangement  of  the  num- 
bers in  the  pseudo-cubes,  and  great  difficulty  was  encoun- 
tered in  balancing  the  central  great  diagonals.  His  pseudo- 


II 


ill 


2 

8 

134 

129 

186 

192 

6 

4 

130 

133 

190 

188 

182 

178 

21 

24 

121 

125 

177 

181 

22 

23 

126 

122 

144 

138 

174 

169 

16 

10 

140 

142 

170 

173 

12 

14 

5 

3 

132 

135 

189 

187 

1 

7 

136 

131 

185 

191 

180 

184 

18 

19 

127 

123 

183 

179 

17 

20 

124 

128 

139 

141 

172 

175 

11 

13 

143 

137 

176 

171 

15 

9 

117 

114 

146 

152 

62 

60 

118 

113 

150 

148 

64 

58 

54 

50 

109 

106 

168 

164 

52 

56 

110 

105 

162 

166 

154 

160 

70 

68 

97 

102 

156 

158 

66 

72 

98 

101 

120 

115 

149 

147 

63 

59 

119 

116 

145 

151 

61 

59 

51 

55 

112 

107 

161 

165 

53 

49 

111 

108 

167 

163 

155 

157 

65 

71 

100 

103 

153 

159 

69 

67 

99 

104 

206 

204 

42 

45 

78 

76 

202 

208 

46 

41 

74 

80 

89 

93 

198 

199 

38 

34 

94 

90 

197 

200 

33 

37 

28 

30 

82 

85 

212 

214 

32 

26 

86 

81 

216 

210 

201 

207 

48 

43 

73 

79 

205 

203 

44 

47 

77 

75 

95 

91 

193 

196 

36 

40 

92 

96 

194 

195 

39 

35 

31 

25 

88 

83 

215 

209 

27 

29 

84 

87 

211 

213 

IV 


V 
Fig.  23. 


VI 


skeleton  is  shown  in  Fig.  21,  where  each  plate  represents 
two  P-planes  of  63,  each  plate  containing  9  pseudo-cubes. 
The  numbers  in  the  subsidiaries  are  shown  in  diagram- 
matic perspective,  the  four  "larger"  numbers  lying  in  the 
anterior  layer,  and  the  four  "smaller"  numbers,  grouped 
in  the  center,  in  the  posterior  layer. 

If  we  use  this  with  the  magic  of  Fig.  22  we  obtain  the 
magic  63  shown  in  Fig.  23. 


THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS.  65 

This  cube  is  non-La  Hireian,  as  is  frequently  the  case 
with  magics  constructed  by  this  method. 

The  scheme  of  pseudo-cubes  for  63  once  found,  we  can 
easily  extend  the  method  to  any  double-of-odd  order  in  the 
following  manner.  Take  the  pseudo-scheme  of  next  lower 
order  [e.  g.,  63  to  make  io3,  io3  to  make  143  etc.] .  To  each 
of  three  outside  plates  of  cubes,  which  meet  at  any  corner 
of  the  skeleton,  apply  a  replica-plate,  and  to  each  of  the 
other  three  faces  a  complementary  to  the  plate  opposed  to 
it,  that  is  a  plate  in  which  each  number  replaces  its  com- 
plementary number  ( i  for  8,  2  for  7,  etc. ) .  We  now  have 
a  properly  balanced  skeleton  for  the  next  double-of-odd 
order,  wanting  only  its  12  edges.  Consider  any  three 
edges  that  meet  at  a  corner  of  the  cube;  they  can  be  com- 
pleted (wanting  their  corner-cubes)  by  placing  in  each 
of  them  any  row  of  cubes  from  the  original  skeleton.  Each 
of  these  three  edges  has  three  other  edges  parallel  to  it, 
two  lying  in  the  same  square  planes  with  it  and  the  third 
diagonally  opposed  to  it.  In  the  former  we  may  place 
edges  complementary  to  the  edge  to  which  they  are  par- 
allel, and  in  the  latter  a  replica  of  the  same.  The  skeleton 
wants  now  only  its  8  corner  pseudo-cubes.  Take  any  cube 
and  place  it  in  four  corners,  no  two  of  which  are  in  the 
same  row,  line,  column,  or  great  diagonal  (e.  g.  B,  C.  E,  H 
in  Fig.  38),  and  in  the  four  remaining  corners  place  its 
complementary  cube.  The  skeleton  is  now  complete,  and 
the  cube  may  be  formed  from  the  odd  magic  of  half  its 
order. 

This  method  we  shall  not  follow  further,  but  shall  now 
turn  to  the  consideration  of  index-cubes,  an  artifice  far 
preferable. 

Before  proceeding  the  reader  should  carefully  study 
the  method  of  the  index-rod  as  used  for  magic  squares 
(pp.  57-61). 

The  reversion  of  a  pair  of  planes  in  each  of  the  three 


66 


THE  MONIST. 


aspects,  as  previously  employed  for  43,  is  evidently  equiva- 
lent to  interchanging  two  numbers  with  their  complemen- 
taries  in  every  row,  line,  and  column  of  the  natural  cube. 
If  therefore  we  define  the  symbol  X  as  implying  that  such 
an  interchange  is  to  be  made  not  only  from  the  cell  in 
which  it  is  placed,  but  also  from  the  three  other  cells  with 
which  it  is  symmetrically  situated  in  regard  to  the  central 
horizontal  and  vertical  bars  of  its  P-plane,  and  can  make 


Fig.  24. 

one  such  symbol  operate  in  every  row,  line  and  column  of 
an  index-cube  whose  edge  is  half  that  of  the  great  cube, 
we  shall  have  secured  the  equivalent  of  the  above-men- 
tioned reversion.  For  example,  a  X  placed  in  the  second 
cell  of  the  top  row  of  any  P-plane  of  43,  will  denote  that  the 
four  numbers  marked  a  in  Fig.  24  are  each  to  be  inter- 
changed with  its  complement,  which  lies  in  the  associated 
cell  in  the  associated  P-plane. 


FIG.  25. 

From  this  it  follows  that  we  shall  have  a  complete 
reversion  scheme  for  any  order  4m,  by  placing  in  every 
row,  line  and  column  of  the  index  (2m)  3,  m  of  the  symbols 
X.  In  the  case  of  orders  47/1+2,  after  placing  m  such  sym- 
bols in  the  cube  (2m-(-i)3,  we  have  still  to  make  the  equiva- 
lent of  one  reversed  plane  in  each  of  the  three  aspects. 
This  amounts  to  making  one  symmetrical  vertical  inter- 
change, one  symmetrical  horizontal  interchange,  and  one 


THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS.  67 

symmetrical  interchange  at  right  angles  to  the  paper-plane 
in  every  row,  line  and  column.  If  we  use  the  symbol  |  to 
denote  such  a  vertical  interchange,  not  only  for  the  cell 
in  which  it  stands,  but  also  for  the  associated  cell,  and  give 
like  meanings  to  —  and  ',  for  horizontal  changes  and 
changes  along  lines,  we  shall  have  made  the  broken  re- 
version when  we  allow  each  of  these  symbols  to  operate 
once  in  every  row,  column  and  line  of  the  index.  For 
example,  a  in  Fig.  25  means  b  in  its  own  P-plane,  and  c  in 
the  associated  P-plane ;  while  d  indicates  that  the  numbers 
lying  in  its  own  P-plane  as  in  e  are  to  be  interchanged,  A 
with  A  and  B  with  B,  with  the  numbers  lying  in  the  asso- 
ciated plane  f.  We  can  always  prepare  the  index,  provided 
the  rod  does  not  contain  a  less  number  of  cells  than  the 
number  of  symbols,  by  the  following  rule,  n  being  the 
order. 

Take  an  index-rod  of  n/2  cells,  n/4  symbols  of  the  form 
X,  (using  the  integral  part  of  11/4.  only),  and  if  there  is 
any  remainder  when  n  is  divided  by  4  add  the  three  sym- 
bols |,  — ,  •.  Now  prepare  an  index  square  in  the  way 
described  on  p.  59,  but  using  the  diagonals  upward  and 
to  the  right  instead  of  upward  to  the  left,7  and  take  this 
square  as  the  first  P-plane  of  an  index-cube.  Fill  every 
great  diagonal  of  the  cube,  running  to  the  right,  down  and 
away,  which  has  a  symbol  in  this  P-plane  cell,  with  repeti- 
tions of  that  symbol.8  This  index-cube  applied  to  the  near, 
left-hand,  top  corner  of  the  natural  n$,  with  the  symbols 
allowed  the  operative  powers  already  defined,  will  make 
the  magic  n$. 

This  method  for  even  orders  applies  universally  with 
the  single  exception  of  63,  and  in  the  case  of  63  we  shall 
presently  show  that  the  broken  reversion  can  still  be  made 

1  Either  way  will  do,  but  it  happens  that  the  former  has  been  used  in  the 
examples  which  follow. 

8  More  briefly,  in  the  language  of  Paths,  the  symbols  are  laid,  in  the  square, 
on  (1,1)  ;  their  repetitions  in  the  cube,  on  (i,  — I,  i). 


68 


THE  MONIST. 


by  scattering  the  symbols  over  the  whole  cube.    The  fol- 
lowing are  index-rods  for  various  cubes. 


43 
83 


123     I     I     JXjXl     |X| 

I43    I   IxHxHxl 


103    |x|l|-|x|.| 

As  in  the  case  of  index-rods  for  squares,  the  first  cell 
may  be  left  blank,  otherwise  it  must  contain  a  X. 


II 


in 


64 

2 

3 

61 

5 

59 

58 

8 

9 

55 

54 

12 

52 

14 

15 

49 

48 

18 

19 

45 

21 

43 

42 

24 

25 

39 

38 

28 

36 

30 

31 

33 

Fig.  26. 

Fig.  26  is  a  43,  made  with  the  index-rod  given  above. 
It  has  only  half  the  numbers  removed  from  their  natural 
places.  Figs.  27  and  28  are  the  index-rod,  index-square 
and  index-cube  for  io3,  and  Fig.  29  is  the  extended  rever- 
sion scheme  obtained  from  these,  in  which  \  and  /  denote 
single  changes  between  associated  cells,  and  the  symbols 
|,  — ,  and  •,  single  changes  parallel  to  columns,  rows,  and 
lines.  Figs.  30  and  31  show  the  resulting  cube. 


I*!*!* I i M 

Index  Rod. 


Index  Square. 


Fig.  27. 


Fig.  28.    Index  Cube. 


THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS. 


\ 

\ 

• 

\ 

- 

- 

/ 

/ 

1 

— 

X 

X 

• 

/ 

/ 

- 

X 

• 

1 

— 

X 

/ 

- 

/ 

s 

• 

1 

- 

X 

/ 

— 

/ 

- 

X 

X 

• 

1 

/ 

/ 

— 

• 

1 

— 

X 

X 

/ 

/ 

— 

• 

1 

— 

X 

X 

/ 

/ 

— 

X 

X 

• 

— 

- 

/ 

/ 

1 

— 

X 

X 

• 

/ 

/ 

— 

1 

- 

X 

X 

• 

/ 

/ 

— 

X 

• 

1 

— 

X 

/ 

— 

/ 

— 

X 

X 

• 

1 

/ 

/ 

— 

- 

\ 

X 

• 

1 

/ 

/ 

— 

• 

1 

— 

X 

X 

/ 

/ 

- 

X 

X 

• 

1 

— 

— 

/ 

s 

/ 

/ 

1 

• 

X 

\ 

1 

/ 

/ 

\ 

X 

• 

/ 

/ 

1 

• 

X 

X 

1 

/ 

/ 

• 

X 

X 

/ 

1 

/ 

X 

• 

X 

/ 

/ 

1 

• 

X 

X 

\ 

/ 

/ 

X 

X 

• 

/ 

/ 

1 

• 

X 

X 

1 

/ 

/ 

• 

X 

X 

/ 

\ 

/ 

X 

. 

X  ( 

/ 

/ 

1 

• 

X 

X 

1 

/ 

/ 

X 

X 

• 

/ 

/ 

1 

• 

X 

X   ( 

1 

/ 

/ 

• 

X 

\ 

/ 

1 

/ 

X 

• 

X 

— 

X 

X 

• 

1 

/ 

/ 

— 

• 

1 

— 

X 

X 

/ 

/ 

— 

• 

X 

X 

/ 

/ 

1 

\ 

\ 

• 

1 

— 

— 

/ 

/ 

1 

— 

X 

X 

• 

/ 

/ 

— 

X 

X 

• 

/ 

/ 

1 

s 

• 

1 

— 

\ 

/ 

— 

/ 

— 

\ 

X 

• 

1 

s 

/ 

— 

X 

X 

• 

1 

/ 

/ 

• 

1 

— 

X 

X 

/ 

/ 

— 

X 

X 

• 

1 

— 

— 

/ 

/ 

X 

X 

• 

1 

/ 

/ 

1 

— 

X 

X 

• 

/ 

/ 

— 

X 

• 

1 

— 

X 

/ 

— 

/ 

X 

• 

X 

/ 

\ 

/ 

1 

/ 

/ 

• 

X 

X 

/ 

1 

/ 

X 

• 

\ 

/ 

— 

/ 

X 

— 

\ 

• 

X 

1 

/ 

/ 

X 

X 

• 

/ 

/ 

1 

• 

X 

X 

/ 

/ 

— 

— 

1 

• 

X 

X 

/ 

1 

/ 

X 

• 

X 

/ 

/ 

\ 

• 

X 

X 

- 

/ 

/ 

1 

• 

X 

X 

— 

/ 

/ 

1 

* 

\ 

X 

\ 

/ 

/ 

• 

X 

X 

— 

/ 

/ 

• 

X 

X 

— 

1 

/ 

/ 

1 

• 

X 

X 

1 

/ 

/ 

X 

X 

• 

— 

/ 

/ 

X 

X 

— 

1 

• 

X 

X 

• 

1 

/ 

/ 

X 

• 

X 

/ 

1 

/ 

X 

X 

• 

/ 

/ 

1 

\ 

X 

• 

1 

/ 

/ 

• 

X 

X 

/ 

/ 

I 

X 

X 

• 

1 

/ 

/ 

\ 

• 

X 

/ 

\ 

/ 

X 

X 

• 

/ 

/ 

\ 

X 

X 

• 

1 

/ 

/ 

• 

X 

X 

/ 

/ 

\ 

X 

X 

• 

\ 

/ 

/ 

X 

• 

X 

/ 

\ 

/ 

X 

\ 

• 

/ 

/ 

\ 

X 

X 

• 

\ 

/ 

/ 

• 

X 

X 

/ 

/ 

\ 

— 

/ 

/ 

• 

X 

X 

— 

\ 

/ 

/ 

— 

- 

\ 

• 

X 

X 

— 

/ 

/ 

X 

X 

— 

\ 

• 

— 

/ 

/ 

\ 

X 

— 

1 

• 

~ 

/ 

/ 

1 

• 

X 

X 

— 

/ 

— 

/ 

X 

— 

1 

• 

X 

/ 

— 

/ 

X 

— 

1 

• 

X 

— 

/ 

/ 

• 

X 

X 

— 

1 

/ 

/ 

— 

— 

1 

• 

X 

X 

/ 

/ 

— 

— 

I 

• 

X 

X 

~ 

/ 

/ 

X 

X 

— 

i 

• 

— 

/ 

/ 

1 

• 

X 

X 

— 

— 

/ 

/ 

! 

• 

Ni 

X 

— 

/ 

— 

/ 

X 

~ 

! 

. 

X 

— 

/ 

/ 

• 

X 

\ 

— 

1 

X 

X 

• 

1 

/ 

/ 

X 

• 

X 

/ 

1 

/ 

• 

X 

X 

/ 

/ 

1 

X 

X 

• 

/ 

/ 

1 

X 

X 

• 

\ 

/ 

/ 

— 

/ 

/ 

1 

• 

X 

X 

— 

— 

/ 

/ 

• 

X 

X 

— 

1 

— 

/ 

/ 

X 

X 

— 

1 

• 

'  / 

— 

/ 

X 

— 

1 

• 

X 

/ 

/ 

- 

- 

1 

• 

X 

X 

Fig.  29.    Extended  Reversion  Scheme  for  io8. 


THE  MONIST. 


100C 

999 

903 

94 

6 

5 

7 

8 

992 

991 

990 

912 

83 

17 

986 

985 

14 

18 

19 

981 

921 

72 

28 

977 

976 

975 

974 

23 

29 

30 

61 

39 

968 

967 

935 

36 

964 

963 

32 

40 

SO 

959 

958 

944 

55 

46 

47 

953 

952 

41 

51 

949 

948 

54 

45 

56 

957 

943 

942 

60 

31 

62 

938 

937 

65 

966 

934 

933 

69 

70 

71 

22 

73 

927 

926 

925 

924 

78 

79 

980 

920 

82 

13 

84 

916 

915 

87 

88 

989 

911 

910 

909 

93 

4 

95 

96 

97 

998 

902 

901 

800 

702 

293 

207 

796 

795 

204 

208 

209 

791 

711 

282 

218 

787 

786 

785 

784 

213 

219 

220 

271 

229 

778 

777 

725 

226 

774 

773 

222 

230 

240 

769 

768 

734 

265 

236 

237 

763 

762 

231 

760 

759 

743 

254 

246 

245 

247 

248 

752 

751 

750 

749 

253 

244 

255 

256 

257 

758 

742 

741 

261 

739 

738 

264 

235 

266 

767 

733 

732 

270 

221 

272 

728 

727 

275 

776 

724 

723 

279 

280 

281 

212 

283 

717 

716 

715 

714 

288 

289 

790 

710 

292 

203 

294 

706 

705 

297 

298 

799 

701 

501 

492 

408 

597 

596 

595 

594 

403 

409 

410 

481 

419 

588 

587 

515 

416 

584 

583 

412 

420 

430 

579 

578 

524 

475 

426 

427 

573 

572 

421 

570 

569 

533 

464 

436 

435 

437 

438 

562 

561 

560 

542 

453 

447 

556 

555 

444 

448 

449 

551 

550 

452 

443 

454 

546 

545 

457 

458 

559 

541 

540 

539 

463 

434 

465 

466 

467 

568 

532 

531 

471 

529 

528 

474 

425 

476 

577 

523 

522 

480 

411 

482 

518 

517 

485 

586 

514 

513 

489 

490 

491 

402 

493 

507 

506 

505 

504 

498 

499 

600 

191 

109 

898 

897 

805 

106 

894 

893 

102 

110 

120 

889 

888 

814 

185 

116 

117 

883 

882 

111 

880 

879 

823 

174 

126 

125 

127 

128 

872 

871 

870 

832 

163 

137 

866 

865 

134 

138 

139 

861 

841 

152 

148 

857 

856 

855 

854 

143 

149 

150 

151 

142 

153 

847 

846 

845 

844 

158 

159 

860 

840 

162 

133 

164 

836 

835 

167 

168 

869 

831 

830 

829 

173 

124 

175 

176 

177 

878 

822 

821 

181 

819 

818 

184 

115 

186 

887 

813 

812 

190 

101 

192 

808 

807 

195 

896 

804 

803 

199 

200 

310 

699 

698 

604 

395 

306 

307 

693 

692 

301 

690 

689 

613 

384 

316 

315 

317 

318 

682 

681 

680 

622 

373 

327 

676 

675 

324 

328 

329 

671 

631 

362 

338 

667 

666 

665 

664 

333 

339 

340 

351 

349 

658 

657 

645 

346 

654 

653 

342 

350 

341 

352 

648 

647 

355 

656 

644 

643 

359 

360 

361 

332 

363 

637 

636 

635 

634 

368 

369 

670 

630 

372 

323 

374 

626 

625 

377 

378 

67,9 

621 

620 

619 

383 

314 

385 

386 

387 

688 

612 

611 

391 

609 

608 

394 

305 

396 

697 

603 

602 

400 

401 

502 

503 

497 

496 

495 

494 

508 

599 

510 

511 

512 

488 

487 

415 

516 

484 

483 

519 

590 

521 

479 

478 

424 

525 

576 

527 

473 

472 

530 

470 

469 

433 

534 

535 

536 

567 

538 

462 

461 

460 

442 

543 

544 

456 

455 

547 

558 

549 

451 

450 

552 

553 

557 

446 

445 

554 

548 

459 

441 

440 

439 

563 

564 

566 

565 

537 

468 

432 

431 

580 

429 

428 

574 

575 

526 

477 

423 

422 

571 

581 

589 

418 

417 

585 

486 

414 

413 

582 

520 

591 

592 

598 

407 

406 

405 

404 

593 

509 

500 

Fig.  30.    First  6  plates  of  io8,  made  from  Fig.  29.    (Sum  =  5005.) 


THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS. 


601 

399 

398 

304 

605 

696 

607 

393 

392 

610 

390 

389 

313 

614 

615 

616 

687 

618 

382 

381 

380 

322 

623 

624 

376 

375 

627 

678 

629 

371 

331 

632 

633 

367 

366 

365 

364 

638 

669 

640 

641 

642 

358 

357 

345 

646 

354 

353 

649 

660 

651 

659 

348 

347 

655 

356 

344 

343 

652 

650 

661 

662 

668 

337 

336 

335 

334 

663 

639 

370 

330 

672 

673 

677 

326 

325 

674 

628 

379 

321 

320 

319 

683 

684 

686 

685 

617 

388 

312 

311 

700 

309 

308 

694 

695 

606 

395 

303 

302 

691 

300 

202 

703 

704 

296 

295 

707 

798 

709 

291 

211 

712 

713 

287 

286 

285 

284 

718 

789 

720 

721 

722 

278 

277 

225 

726 

274 

273 

729 

780 

731 

269 

268 

234 

735 

766 

737 

263 

262 

740 

260 

259 

243 

744 

745 

746 

757 

748 

252 

251 

250 

249 

753 

754 

756 

755 

747 

258 

242 

241 

770 

239 

238 

764 

765 

736 

267 

233 

232 

761 

771 

779 

228 

227 

775 

276 

224 

223 

772 

730 

781 

782 

788 

217 

216 

215 

214 

783 

719 

290 

210 

792 

793 

797 

206 

205 

794 

708 

299 

201 

801 

802 

198 

197 

105 

806 

194 

193 

809 

900 

811 

189 

188 

114 

815 

886 

817 

18.1 

182 

820 

180 

179 

123 

824 

825 

826 

877 

828 

172 

171 

170 

132 

833 

834 

166 

165 

837 

868 

839 

161 

141 

842 

843 

157 

156 

155 

154 

848 

859 

850 

851 

852 

858 

147 

146 

145 

144 

853 

849 

160 

140 

862 

863 

867 

136 

135 

864 

838 

169 

131 

130 

129 

873 

874 

876 

875 

827 

178 

122 

121 

890 

119 

118 

884 

885 

816 

187 

113 

112 

881 

891 

899 

108 

107 

893 

196 

104 

103 

892 

810 

100 

99 

3 

904 

905 

906 

997 

908 

92 

91 

90 

12 

913 

914 

86 

85 

917 

988 

919 

81 

21 

922 

923 

77 

76 

75 

74 

928 

979 

930 

931 

932 

68 

67 

35 

936 

64 

63 

939 

970 

941 

59 

58 

44 

945 

956 

947 

53 

52 

950 

960 

49 

48 

954 

955 

946 

57 

43 

42 

951 

961 

969 

38 

37 

965 

66 

34 

33 

962 

940 

971 

972 

978 

27 

26 

25 

24 

973 

929 

80 

20 

982 

983 

987 

16 

15 

984 

918 

89 

11 

10 

9 

993 

994 

996 

995 

907 

98 

2 

1 

Fig.  31.    Last  4  plates  of  10',  made  from  Fig.  29.    (Sum  =  5005.) 

If  we  attack  63  by  the  general  rule,  we  find  4  symbols, 
X,  — ,  |,  *,  and  only  3  cells  in  the  rod;  the  construction  is 
therefore  impossible.  Suppose  we  construct  an  index-cube 
from  the  rod  |x|i|-|,  we  shall  find  it  impossible  to  distribute 
the  remaining  symbol  H  in  the  extended  reversion-scheme 
obtained  from  this  index.  The  feat,  however,  is  possible 
if  we  make  (for  this  case  only)  a  slight  change  in  the 
meanings  of  |  and  — .  By  the  general  rule  X  operates  on 
4  cells  in  its  own  P-plane,  where,  by  the  rule  of  association, 

i  with  6 


the  planes  are  paired  thus: 


In  interpreting 


THE  MONIST. 


Thus  for 


1  with  5 

2  "      4 

3  "     6 


This 


the  meanings  of  |  and  — ,  in  this  special  case,  we  must  make 
a  cyclic  change  in  the  right-hand  column  of  this  little  table. 

i  with  4 

and  for  "— "     2     "     6 
3          5 

means  that  a  M,  for  example,  in  the  second  P-plane  has  its 
usual  meaning  in  that  plane,  and  also  acts  on  the  two  cells 
which  would  be  the  associated  cells  if  the  4th  plane  were 
to  become  the  5th,  etc.  If  we  extend  this  scheme,  there 
will  be  just  room  to  properly  distribute  the  M's  in  the  two 
parallelepipeds  which  form  the  right-hand  upper  and  left- 
hand  lower  quarters  of  the  cube,  as  shown  in  Fig.  32. 


ii 


IV  V  VI 

Fig.  32.    Extended  Reversion-Scheme  for  6*. 

This  scheme  produces  the  cube  shown  below,  which  is 
magic  on  its  36  rows,  36  columns,  36  lines,  and  on  its  4 
central  great  diagonals. 

Fig.  32  is  the  identical  scheme  discovered  by  Firth  in 
1889,  and  was  obtained  a  few  months  later  than  the  pseudo- 
skeleton  shown  in  Fig.  21.  A  year  or  two  earlier  he  had 
discovered  the  broken  reversion  for  squares  of  even  order, 
but  he  never  generalized  the  method,  or  conceived  the  idea 
of  an  index-cube.  The  development  of  the  method  as  here 
described  was  worked  out  by  the  present  writer  in  1894. 


THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS. 


73 


About  the  same  time  Rouse  Ball,  of  Trinity  College,  Cam- 
bridge, independently  arrived  at  the  method  of  reversions 
for  squares  (compare  the  earlier  editions  of  his  Mathemat- 
ical Recreations,  Macmillan),  and  in  the  last  edition,  1905, 
he  adopts  the  idea  of  an  index-square ;  but  he  makes  no  ap- 
plication to  cubes  or  higher  dimensions.  There  is  reason 
to  believe,  however,  that  the  idea  of  reversions  by  means 
of  an  index-square  was  known  to  Fermat.  In  his  letter  to 


ii 


in 


216 

32 

4 

3 

185 

211 

25 

11 

208 

207 

8 

192 

18 

203 

21 

196 

200 

13 

199 

197 

15 

22 

194 

24 

7 

206 

190 

189 

29 

30 

186 

2 

213 

34 

35 

181 

67 

41 

178 

177 

38 

150 

48 

173 

63 

154 

170 

43 

168 

56 

52 

51 

161 

163 

162 

50 

165 

58 

59 

157 

169 

155 

45 

64 

152 

66 

37 

176 

148 

147 

71 

72 

78 

143 

105 

112 

140 

73 

138 

98 

82 

81 

119 

133 

91 

89 

130 

129 

86 

126 

85 

128 

124 

123 

95 

96 

120 

80 

135 

100 

101 

115 

139 

113 

75 

106 

110 

108 

109 

107 

111 

76 

104 

144 

102 

116 

117 

136 

83 

97 

121 

122 

94 

93 

131 

90 

132 

92 

88 

87 

125 

127 

84 

137 

99 

118 

134 

79 

103 

77 

142 

141 

74 

114 

145 

146 

70 

69 

179 

42 

151 

65 

153 

46 

62 

174 

60 

158 

159 

166 

53 

55 

54 

167 

57 

160 

164 

49 

61 

47 

172 

171 

44 

156 

180 

68 

40 

39 

149 

175 

36 

182 

183 

214 

5 

31 

187 

188 

28 

27 

209 

12 

193 

23 

195 

16 

20 

204 

19 

17 

202 

201 

14 

198 

210 

26 

10 

9 

191 

205 

6 

215 

33 

184 

212 

A 

IV 


VI 


Fig.  33,  made  from  Fig.  32.    Sum  =  651. 


Mersenne  of  April  i,  1640,  (CEuvres  de  Fermat,  Vol.  II, 
p.  193),  he  gives  the  square  of  order  6  shown  in  Fig.  34. 
This  is  obtained  by  applying  the  index  (Fig.  35)  to  the 
bottom  left-hand  corner  of  the  natural  square  written  from 
below  upwards,  i.  e.,  with  the  numbers  i  to  6  in  the  bottom 
row,  7  to  12  in  the  row  above  this,  etc.  There  is  nothing 
surprising  in  this  method  of  writing  the  natural  square, 
in  fact  it  is  suggested  by  the  conventions  of  Cartesian 
geometry,  with  which  Fermat  was  familiar.  There  is  a 


74 


THE  MONIST. 


much  later  similar  instance:  Cayley,  in  1890,  dealing  with 
"Latin  squares,"  writes  from  below  upwards,  although 
Euler,  in  his  original  Memoire  (1782),  wrote  from  above 
downwards.  Another  square  of  order  6,  given  by  Fermat, 
in  the  same  place,  is  made  from  the  same  index,  but  is  dis- 
guised because  he  uses  a  "deformed"  natural  square. 


6 

32 

3 

34 

35 

1 

7 

11 

27 

28 

8 

30 

19 

14 

16 

15 

23 

24 

18 

20 

22 

21 

17 

13 

25 

29 

10 

9 

26 

12 

36 

5 

33 

4 

2 

31 

Fig.  34- 


Fig.  35- 


It  is  interesting  to  note  that  all  these  reversion  magics 
(unlike  those  made  by  Thompson's  method),  are  La  Hire- 
ian,  and  also  that  the  La  Hireian  scheme  can  be  obtained 
by  turning  a  single  outline  on  itself.  To  explain  this  state- 
ment we  will  translate  the  square  in  Fig.  12  into  the  scale 

A 


55 

04 

52 

03 

01 

50 

40 

44 

13 

12 

41 

15 

25 

31 

33 

32 

24 

20 

30 

21 

23 

22 

34 

35 

10 

14 

42 

43 

11 

45 

05 

51 

02 

53 

54 

00 

Fig.  36. 

whose  radix  is  6,  first  decreasing  every  number  by  unity. 
This  last  artifice  is  merely  equivalent  to  using  the  n2  con- 
secutive numbers  from  o  to  n2 — I,  instead  of  from  i  to  n2, 
and  is  convenient  because  it  brings  the  scheme  of  units 
and  the  scheme  of  6's  digits  into  uniformity. 

If  we  examine  this  result  as  shown  in  Fig.  36  we 


THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS. 


75 


find  that  the  scheme  for  units  can  be  converted  into  that 
for  the  6's,  by  turning  the  skeleton  through  180°  about 
the  axis  AB;  that  is  to  say,  a  single  outline  turned  upon 
itself  will  produce  the  magic. 


ii 


in 


555 

051 

003 

002 

504 

550 

040 

014 

543 

542 

Oil 

515 

025 

534 

032 

523 

531 

020 

530 

524 

022 

033 

521 

035 

010 

541 

513 

512 

044 

045 

505 

001 

552 

053 

054 

500 

150 

104 

453 

452 

101 

405 

115 

444 

142 

413 

441 

110 

435 

131 

123 

122 

424 

430 

425 

121 

432 

133 

134 

420 

440 

414 

112 

143 

411 

145 

100 

451 

403 

402 

154 

155 

205 

354 

252 

303 

351 

200 

345 

241 

213 

212 

314 

340 

230 

224 

333 

332 

221 

325 

220 

331 

323 

322 

234 

235 

315 

211 

342 

243 

244 

310 

350 

304 

202 

253 

301 

255 

300 

254 

302 

203 

251 

355 

245 

311 

312 

343 

214 

240 

320 

321 

233 

232 

334 

225 

335 

231 

223 

222 

324 

330 

215 

344 

242 

313 

341 

210 

250 

204 

353 

352 

201 

305 

400 

401 

153 

152 

454 

105 

410 

144 

412 

113 

141 

445 

135 

421 

422 

433 

124 

130 

125 

434 

132 

423 

431 

120 

140 

114 

443 

442 

111 

415 

455 

151 

103 

102 

404 

450 

055 

501 

502 

553 

004 

050 

510 

511 

043 

042 

544 

015 

520 

034 

522 

023 

031 

535 

030 

024 

533 

532 

021 

525 

545 

041 

013 

012 

514 

#0 

005 

554 

052 

503 

551 

000 

Fig.  37- 

The  same  is  true  of  the  cube;  that  is,  just  as  we  can 
obtain  a  La  Hireian  scheme  for  a  square  by  turning  a 
single  square  outline  once  upon  itself,  so  a  similar  scheme 
for  a  cube  can  be  obtained  by  turning  a  cubic  outline 


Fig.  38.  Fig.  39.  Fig.  40. 


twice  upon  itself.  If  we  reduce  all  the  numbers  in  Fig. 
33  by  unity  and  then  "unroll"  the  cube,  we  get  the  La  Hire- 
ian scheme  of  Fig.  37  in  the  scale  radix  6. 

If  now  we  represent  the  skeleton  of  the62>s :  (left-hand) 
digits  by  Fig.  38,  and  give  this  cube  the  "twist"  indicated 


THE  MONIST. 


by  Fig.  39,  we  shall  get  the  skeleton  of  the  6's  (middle) 
digits,  and  the  turn  suggested  by  Fig.  40  gives  that  of  the 
units  (right-hand)  digits.  Thus  a  single  outline  turned 
twice  upon  itself  gives  the  scheme. 

We  can  construct  any  crude  magic  octahedroid9  of 


Fig.  41,  ist  reversion.    Fig.  42,  2d  reversion.    Fig.  43,  3d  reversion. 


as 


double-of-Jeven  order,    by  the  method  of  reversions, 
shown  with  44  in  Figs.  41  to  44. 

The  first  three  reversions  will  be  easily  understood 
from  the  figures,  but  the  fourth  requires  some  explanation 
It  actually  amounts  to  an  interchange  between  every  pair 

A  B    C  D 


Fig.  44,  4th  reversion. 

of  numbers  in  associated  cells  of  the  parallelepiped  formed 
by  the  two  central  cubical  sections.  If  the  reader  will  use 
a  box  or  some  other  "rectangular"  solid  as  a  model,  and 
number  the  8  corners,  he  will  find  that  such  a  change  can- 
not be  effected  in  three-dimensional  space  by  turning  the 


DIMENSIONS 

REGULAR  FIGURE 

BOUNDARIES 

2 

3 
4 
etc. 

Tetragon  (or  square) 
Hexahedron  (cube) 
Octahedroid 
etc. 

4  one-dimensional  straight  lines 
6  two-dimensional  squares 
8  three-dimensional  cubes 
etc. 

THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS. 


77 


parallelepiped  as  a  whole,  on  the  same  principle  that  a  right 
hand  cannot,  by  any  turn,  be  converted  into  a  left  hand. 
But  such  a  change  can  be  produced  by  a  single  turn  in 
4-dimensional  space;  in  fact  this  last  reversion  is  made 
with  regard  to  an  axis  in  the  4th,  or  imaginary  direction. 


1 

2 

3 

4 

248 

247 

246 

245 

252 

251 

250 

249 

13 

14 

15 

16 

129 

130 

131 

132 

120 

119 

118 

117 

124 

123 

122 

121 

141 

142 

143 

144 

Fig-  45- 


The  following  four  figures  (45-48)  show  each  stage  of  the 
process,  and  if  the  reader  will  compare  them  with  the  re- 
sults of  a  like  series  of  reversions  made  from  a  different 
aspect  of  the  natural  octahedroid,  he  will  find  that  the 
"imaginary''  reversion  then  becomes  a  real  reversion,  while 


THE  MONIST. 


one  of  the  reversions  which  was  real  becomes  imaginary. 
Fig.  45  is  the  natural  44  after  the  first  reversion,  magic  in 
columns  only;  Fig.  46  is  Fig. 45  after  the  second  reversion, 
magic  in  rows  and  columns;  Fig.  47  is  Fig.  46  after  the 
third  reversion,  magic  in  rows,  columns  and  lines;  and 


33 

222 

223 

36 

216 

43 

42 

213 

220 

39 

38 

217 

45 

210 

211 

48 

49 

206 

207 

52 

200 

59 

58 

197 

204 

55 

54 

201 

61 

194 

195 

64 

65 

190 

191 

68 

184 

75 

74 

181 

188 

71 

70 

185 

77 

178 

179 

80 

81 

174 

175 

84 

168 

91 

90 

165 

172 

87 

86 

169 

93 

162 

163 

96 

97 

158 

159 

100 

152 

107 

106 

149 

156 

103 

102 

153 

109 

146 

147 

112 

113 

142 

143 

116 

136 

123 

122 

133 

140 

119 

118 

137 

125 

130 

131 

128 

129 

126 

127 

132 

120 

139 

138 

117 

124 

135 

134 

121 

141 

114 

115 

144 

145 

110 

111 

148 

104 

155 

154 

101 

108 

151 

150 

105 

157 

98 

99 

160 

161 

94 

95 

164 

88 

171 

170 

85 

92 

167 

166 

89 

173 

82 

83 

176 

177 

78 

79 

180 

72 

187 

186 

69 

76 

183 

182 

73 

189 

66 

67 

192 

193 

62 

63 

196 

56 

203 

202 

53 

60 

199 

198 

57 

205 

50 

51 

208 

209 

46 

47 

212 

40 

219 

218 

37 

44 

215 

214 

41 

221 

34 

35 

224 

225 

30 

31 

228 

24 

235 

234 

21 

28 

231 

230 

25 

237 

18 

19 

240 

Fig.  46. 


Fig.  48  is  Fig.  47  after  the  fourth  reversion,  magic  in  rows, 
columns,  lines  and  i's,  =  crude  magic  44.  The  symbol  i 
denotes  series  of  cells  parallel  to  the  imaginary  edge. 

Fig.  48  is  magic  on  its  64  rows,  64  columns,  64  lines, 
and  64  i's,  and  on  its  8  central  hyperdiagonals.    Through- 


THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS. 


79 


out  the  above  operations  the  columns  of  squares  have  been 
taken  as  forming  the  four  cells  of  the  Pi-aspect  ;10  the  rows 
of  squares  taken  to  form  cubes,  of  course,  show  the  P2- 
aspect. 


1 

254 

255 

4 

248 

11 

10 

245 

252 

7 

6 

249 

13 

242 

243 

16 

65 

190 

191 

68 

184 

75 

74 

181 

188 

71 

70 

185 

77 

178 

179 

80 

224 

35 

34 

221 

41 

214 

215 

44 

37 

218 

219 

40 

212 

47 

46 

209 

48 

211 

210 

45 

217 

38 

39 

220 

213 

42 

43 

216 

36 

223 

222 

33 

177 

78 

79 

180 

72 

187 

186 

69 

76 

183 

182 

73 

189 

66 

67 

192 

241 

14 

15 

244 

8 

251 

250 

5 

12 

247 

246 

9 

253 

2 

3 

256 

Fig.  47- 

This  construction  has  been  introduced  merely  to  ac- 
centuate the  analogy  between  magics  of  various  dimen- 
sions; we  might  have  obtained  the  magic  44  much  more 

10  Since  the  4th  dimension  is  the  square  of  the  second,  two  aspects  of  the 
pctahedroid  are  shown  in  the  presentation  plane.  The  3d  and  4th  aspects  are 
in  H-planes  and  V-planes.  Since  there  are  two  P-plane  aspects  it  might  appear 
that  each  would  produce  a  different  H-plane  and  V-plane  aspect;  but  this  is 
a  delusion. 


8o 


THE  MONIST. 


rapidly  by  a  method  analogous  to  that  used  for  43  (Fig. 
26).  We  have  simply  to  interchange  each  number  in  the 
natural  octahedroid  occupying  a  cell  marked  tx]  in  Fig.  49, 
with  its  complementary  number  lying  in  the  associated  cell 


1  > 

254 

255 

4 

248 

11 

10 

245 

252 

7 

6 

249 

13 

242 

243 

16 

128 

131 

130 

125 

137 

118 

119 

140 

133 

122 

123 

136 

116 

143 

142 

113 

161 

94 

95 

164 

88 

171 

170 

85 

92 

167 

166 

89 

173 

82 

83 

176 

145 

HO 

111 

148 

104 

155 

154 

101 

108 

151 

150 

105 

157 

98 

99 

160 

48 

211 

210 

45 

217 

38 

39 

220 

213 

42 

43 

216 

36 

223 

222 

33 

241 

14 

15 

244 

8 

251 

250 

5 

12 

247 

246 

9 

253 

2 

3 

256 

Fig.  48. 

of  the  associated  cube.     Fig.  49  is  the  extended  skew- 
reversion  scheme  from  the  index-rod  I   |x|. 

All  magic  octahedroids  of  double-of-odd  order  >io4 
can  be  constructed  by  the  index-rod,  for  just  as  we  con- 
struct an  index-square  from  the  rod,  and  an  index-cube 
from  the  square,  so  we  can  construct  an  index-octrahedroid 


THE  THEORY  OF  REVERSIONS. 


8l 


from  the  cube.    The  magics  64  and  io4  have  not  the  capac- 
ity for  construction  by  the  general  rule,  but  they  may  be 


X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

X 

Fig.  49.    Skew  Reversion  for  4*. 

obtained  by  scattering  the  symbols  over  the  whole  figure 
as  we  did  with  63. 

C.  PLANCK. 
HAYWARD'S  HEATH,  ENGLAND. 


TWO  STUDIES  IN  SUGGESTION. 

THE   BOXERS. 

A^L  the  world  knows  how  the  North  of  China  was  con- 
vulsed in  the  year  1900  by  a  wave  of  patriotic  feeling 
stimulated  by  certain  enthusiasts  named  by  foreigners 
"Boxers."  It  is  not  quite  so  well  known  that  this  enthu- 
siasm was  propagated  by  recognized  methods  of  psychical 
excitement. 

This  society,  known  as  the  /  ho  ch'uan  or  "Public  Har- 
mony Fists,"  arose  in  Shantung  province,  and,  by  the  con- 
nivance of  certain  local  officials  whose  national  feelings 
outran  their  prudence,  expanded  and  spread  throughout 
that  province  and  into  the  adjoining  one  of  Chin-Li.  In 
the  course  of  the  summer  of  1900  all  the  provinces  north 
of  the  Yellow  River  were  permeated,  the  matter  coming 
to  a  climax  in  the  famous  siege  of  the  Peking  legations. 

All  narrators  agree  that  certain  rites  were  performed 
by  the  propagators  of  the  movement,  which  came  to  receive 
the  vague  title  of  "Boxer  drill." 

The  following  quotations  will  indicate  the  general  na- 
ture of  this  process : 

A.  "They  were  not  successful  in  getting  the  people  to 
take  it  up  at  first,  so  they  began  with  boys  ten  to  twelve 
years  of  age.  . .  .  After  a  few  days  it  grew  very  rapidly. 
The  drill,  if  it  may  be  called  so,  consists  in  the  boy  repeating 
four  short  lines  of  some  mystic  words,  and  bowing  to  the 
south  and  falling  backwards,  when  he  goes  into  a  trance, 


TWO  STUDIES  IN  SUGGESTION.  83 

remaining  lying  on  his  back  for  an  indefinite  time,  when 
he  rises  and  is  endowed  with  wonderful  strength,  boys 
of  twelve  being  as  strong  as  men.  They  brandish  swords 
and  spears,  not  seeming  to  try  to  be  skilful  in  handling 
them,  but  merely  to  show  strength  and  place  themselves 
under  the  protection  of  their  symbols.  They  claim  to  be 
invulnerable." — Rev.  C.  W.  Price  of  Fen-Chou-Fu,  Shansi, 
in  With  Fire  and  Sword  in  Shan-si  (Diary,  June  i,  1900). 

B.  "Drill  consisted  in  incense  before  a  tablet.  . .  .and 
then  working  themselves  by  gymnastics,  etc.,  into  a  state 
when  they  were  no  longer  masters  of  themselves,  but  be- 
came unconscious.  After  remaining  in  this  state  for  some 
time  they  would  rise,  declaring  themselves  possessed  by 
the  spirit  of  one  of  the  heroes  of  antiquity.  In  this  state 
they  could  perform  great  feats,  but  the  chief  mark  was 
that  they  were  invulnerable.  Swords  did  not  hurt,  and 
they  knocked  their  heads  till  great  bumps  appeared,  but 
never  felt  it." — Slightly  abridged  from  Mrs.  A.  H.  Mateer, 
Siege  Days,  New  York,  Redell. 

According  to  the  Rev.  G.  T.  Candlin  (author  of  Chi- 
nese Fiction,  Chicago,  Open  Court  Pub.  Co.)  who  was  in 
Tung  Shan  during  the  outbreak,  the  "four  mystic  lines" 
were  as  follows,  and  were  accompanied  by  certain  postures 
(bowing  in  the  Chinese  ceremonial  style  of  prostrating 
and  beating  the  head  on  the  ground) : 

T'ien  ta,  T'ien  chiu  k'ai 
Ti  ta,  Ti  chiu  k'ai 
Yao  hstieh  I  ho  ch'uan 
Huan  te  Shih  Fu  lai. 

"Beat  the  heaven,  the  heaven  will  open; 
Beat  earth,  and  earth  will  open; 
Desire  to  learn  the  public-harmony-force1 
Also  get  the  masters  to  come." 

He  has  also  expressed  an  opinion  that  Buddhist  and 
Taoist  priests  were  connected  in  some  way  with  the  move- 

1  Ch'uan  is  "fist"  but  has  in  this  case  the  sense  of  the  power  of  the  fist. 


84  THE  MONIST. 

ment  and  employed  hypnotic  methods.  In  this  connection 
it  is  interesting  to  note  that  Putnam  Weale  in  his  famous 
book  Indiscreet  Letters  from  Peking  speaks  of  a  temple 
which  had  been  specially  frequented  by  Boxers,  and  that 
native  Christians  had  been  murdered  there,  presumably  in 
some  sense  as  sacrifices.  He  also  mentions  the  large  part 
played  by  boys  in  the  movement. 

If  we  survey  the  whole  of  the  information  available 
(of  which  the  above  is  but  a  representative  selection)  it  is 
evident  that 

1.  Ceremonial  rites  including  prostrations  and  chants 
formed  the  initial  feature  of  the  process  and  were  pro- 
longed until  the  cerebral  consciousness  became  dormant; 

2.  A  period  of  trance  supervened; 

3.  The  trance  was  followed  by  a  period  of  great  excite- 
ment in  which  excessive  muscular  energy  and  anesthesia 
were  shown; 

4.  Boys  were  more  subject  to  the  influence  than  men, 
but  once  started  it  was  very  contagious ; 

5.  The  dominant  idea  was  to  expel  the  foreigner,  and 
this  was  readily  acceptable  to  the  people  at  the  time  on 
account  of  public  events.    This  was  shown  in  the  motto 

Pao  ch'ing,  mieh  yang, 
"Guard  the  Ch'ing  Dynasty,  destroy  the  foreigner." 

The  Chinese  are  peculiarly  subject  to  the  suggestive 
value  of  epigrammatic  sentences  like  this,  and  in  this  case 
we  have  not  far  to  look  for  the  master-thought. 

The  belief  in  possession  by  spirits  is  of  course  not  pe- 
culiar to  them,  but  an  example  of  it  in  China  is  given  in 
the  Rev.  MacGowan's  book  on  Side  Lights  on  Chinese 
Life,  quoted  in  my  article  on  "Chinese  Philosophy  and 
Magic"  in  the  Journal  of  the  Royal  Society  of  Arts,  April 
21,  1911.  The  Confucian  philosophy  as  expounded  by 
Chu  Hsi  implies  that  the  vital  spirit  in  men  is  one  and 


TWO  STUDIES  IN  SUGGESTION.  85 

the  same  with  that  of  their  ancestors,  so  that  it  is  not 
difficult  for  them  to  conceive  that  the  peculiar  individuality 
of  an  heroic  ancestor  may  well  up  in  the  soul  of  his  descen- 
dant. Such  an  idea  forms  a  simple  (and  to  them,  rational) 
explanation  of  the  enthusiasm  and  modification  of  personal- 
ity which  immediately  succeeded  the  trance. 

The  words  Shih-Fu,  "master,"  may  be  taken  as  singu- 
lar, plural  or  general,  just  as  one  thinks  fit.  Probably  the 
intellects  of  the  I  Ho  Ch'iian  would  instruct  their  followers 
specially  as  to  the  particular  incarnation  with  which  they 
happened  to  be  favored. 

The  word  ta,  "to  beat,"  is  of  very  great  idiomatic  power 
in  Mandarin  speech,  and  must  not  necessarily  be  taken  in 
its  literal  sense.  It  can  mean  "to  appeal  to,"  or  "to  serve," 
and  undoubtedly  is  to  be  so  taken. 

Heaven  and  earth  are  of  course  the  great  Chinese 
polarities,  the  reservoirs  of  positive  and  negative  energy. 

The  general  sense  of  the  chants  is  then  that  heavenly 
and  earthly  powers  will  respond  if  called  upon,  so  that  one 
should  desire  the  patriotic  vigor  and  call  upon  the  dead  to 
enthuse  one. 

The  phenomenon  of  anesthesia  (incorrectly  regarded  as 
invulnerability)  is  of  course  a  usual  concomitant  of  hystero- 
epilepsy.  The  dauntless  frenzy  of  the  Mahdi's  followers 
undoubtedly  sprang  from  the  same  conviction  of  personal 
safety,  their  master  having  assured  them  that  neither 
sword  nor  bullet  could  harm  them. 

The  success  of  the  influence  with  boys  indicates  the 
hindrances  which  the  auto-suggestions  of  reason  placed  in 
the  way  of  the  submission  of  adults.  Boys  have  universally 
been  employed  as  "mediums"  in  the  East.2 

An  interesting  point  in  the  whole  question  is  whether 
it  was  incepted  by  intellects  who  understand  more  or  less 
well  the  laws  of  psychology,  or  merely  arose  from  the  nat- 

*  See  Lane's  Modern  Egyptians. 


86  THE  MONIST. 

ural  aggregation  of  anti-foreign  influences.  It  will  per- 
haps be  useful  to  consider  what  are  the  Chinese  notions  as 
to  psychology. 

Primitive  Psychology  in  China. 

The  only  character  in  the  ancient  Chinese  hieroglyph- 
ics which  takes  a  permanent  place  in  psychological  ideas  is 
hsin,  "the  heart."    Egyptian  and  Semitic  literature  show 
the  same  feature.     In  all  three  languages  other  symbols 
are  used  for  external  quasi-psychical  phenomena,  but  the 
individual's  own  feelings  and  thoughts  are  almost  all  ex- 
pressed in  terms  of  the  "heart."    In  other  words,  the  heart 
was  regarded  as  the  seat  of  the  intellect  and  emotions, 
presumably  because  the  emotions  when  of  a  violent  char- 
acter affect  t|ie  "sympathetic"  or  ganglionic  nervous  sys- 
tem and  the  heart  shows  the  disturbance  most  strongly. 
As  example  we  cite  the  following  compound  characters: 
The  term  "virtue"  consists  of  a  radical  meaning  "to  walk" 
combined  with  "straight"  and  "heart." 
The  character  "like"  above  "heart"  means  "reciprocity." 
The  character  "slave"  above  "heart"  means  "anger." 
The  character  "receive"  above  "heart"  means  "love." 
The  character  "inferior"  above  "heart"  means  "hate." 
The  character  "scholar"  above  "heart"  means  "will." 
The  character  "mutual"  above  "heart"  means  "think." 
The  character  "middle"  above  "heart"  means  "sincerity/1 

Dual  Consciousness  in  Chinese  Psychology. 

The  distinction  between  the  central  energies  of  the 
cerebro-spinal  nervous  system  and  those  of  the  ganglionic 
(sympathetic)  system  has  only  recently  been  made  out 
(See  Hudson's  Law  of  Psychic  Phenomena)  and  is  clearly 
adumbrated  in  the  scholastic  animus  and  anima  and  the  Chi- 
nese hun  and  p'o.  These  are  the  personalized  forms  of  the 
psychic  quantities  shen  and  kuei.  The  energies  are  re- 


TWO  STUDIES  IN  SUGGESTION.  87 

spectively  termed  ch'i  and  ching,  and  are  regarded  as 
special  forms  of  the  positive  (yang}  and  negative  (yin) 
polarities  of  energy.  The  hun  is  supposed  to  wander  at 
times  during  life  and  after  death,  while  the  pfo  controls  the 
animal  functions  and  only  persists  in  a  shadowy  form  after 
death.  Stimulated,  the  hun  manifests  as  chih  the  will, 
while  the  p'o  is  the  seat  of  emotion,  Ming. 

The  ideas  outlined  above  are  almost  all  that  can  be 
gleaned  from  the  ordinarily  accessible  native  works.  The 
practice  of  meditation  in  Buddhist  and  Taoist  monasteries 
is  undoubtedly  based  on  careful  observations  of  the  re- 
sults of  "religious  exercises."  The  Rev.  Timothy  Richard 
of  Shanghai  has  translated  a  book  which  he  calls  the 
"Guide  to  Buddhahood,"  Hsiian  Fo  pfu  (literally  "The 
Record  of  the  Selection  of  the  Buddha"). 

This  is  a  graduated  statement  of  the  development  of 
the  soul  on  ecstatic  lines  and  reminds  one  of  St.  Teresa's 
Castillo  Interior.  Commencing  with  introspection  of  mor- 
als, it  passes  to  contemplation  of  virtue  and  then  through 
a  whole  series  of  meditations  on  mythological  concepts, 
which  will  culminate  in  Nirvana.  The  analogy  with  the 
stages  of  apotheosis  described  by  Plotinus  and  the  Sufis 
is  obvious. 

An  acquaintance  with  such  mental  conditions  (prob- 
ably accompanied  by  strange  phenomena  in  various  cases 
due  to  the  nervous  idiosyncrasies  of  the  individual)  would 
be  quite  sufficient  to  provide  a  working  hypothesis  for  such 
a  movement  as  that  of  the  I-ho-ch'uan.  By  those  who  care 
for  the  terminology  it  may  be  legitimately  called  "black 
magic,"  although  it  amounts  to  very  little  more  than  the 
control  exerted  by  religious  fanatics  generally  on  those 
of  their  disciples  who  have  been  "worked  up"  to  the  point 
of  hysteria.  There  is  this  difference,  however,  that  in  the 
East  the  moving  spirits  generally  know  to  some  extent 
what  they  are  doing,  whereas  in  the  West  this  knowledge 


85  THE  MONIST. 

is  only  possessed  by  those  who  have  little  or  no  occasion 
to  employ  it. 

In  conclusion  the  writer  would  point  out  that  the  normal 
Chinese  mind  is  very  acute,  but  conservative  and  lacking 
initiative.  When  excited  however  beyond  a  certain  point, 
it  exhibits  a  wild  frenzy  which  is  utterly  reckless  of  con- 
sequences. These  characteristics  of  course  are  not  peculiar 
to  the  people  but  seem,  at  least  to  the  writer,  to  be  more 
marked  than  in  the  European.  Speaking  broadly,  the 
European  in  China  behaves  as  if  he  had  little  or  no  self- 
control  in  small  matters,  whereas  in  important  things  he 
generally  becomes  cool.  With  the  Chinese  it  is  the  re- 
verse, perfect  nonchalance  in  ordinary  affairs  but  imper- 
fect balance  in  large  ones.  The  writer  does  not  of  course 
suggest  this  is  universally  true  of  individuals. 

THE  MAGICAL  USE  OF  BLOOD. 

In  the  highest  and  lowest  of  ceremonial  religions,  and 
almost  universally  in  connection  with  magic,  we  find  ref- 
erences to  the  potency  of  blood. 

The  standard  methods  of  ancestor-worship3  include  a 
bloody  sacrifice  to  the  manes,  and  an  anointing  with  blood 
of  the  eidolon  which  represents  the  spirit.  Primitively  the 
blood  is  placed  in  the  mouth  of  the  figure.  Almost  in  all 
cases  it  is  conceived  as  providing  vitality  to  the  ghost.  The 
invocation  of  the  ghosts  in  the  Odyssey  is  a  typical  case. 
The  Pentateuch  says  "the  blood  is  the  life,"  and  to  this 
day  the  Jews  abstain  from  meat  which  is  not  kosher,  i.  e., 
deprived  of  blood. 

In  China  there  are  similar  notions.  Thus  under  the 
character  hsueh,  "blood,"  in  Giles's  Dictionary  the  follow- 
ing phrase  occurs : 

Jen  hsueh  chih  wei  yeh  huo  yeh,  "Man's  blood  causes 
strange  fire." 

'  See  Grant  Allen's  Evolution  of  the  Idea  of  God. 


TWO  STUDIES  IN  SUGGESTION.  89 

This  emanation  from  blood  is  also  termed  kuei  huo, 
"ghostly  fire." 

Again  in  the  medieval  books  on  magic  we  find  that 

1.  Numerous  prescriptions  and  charms  require  blood, 
and  even  bloody  sacrifices  are  necessary  in  some  cases ; 

2.  Books  professing  to  teach  only  pure  theurgy  recom- 
mend the  practitioner  to  avoid  the  use  of  blood. 

The  aversion  for  blood  also  appears  in  the  practices 
of  bloodless  execution  employed  by  the  Turks  and  the  In- 
quisition. 

The  atoning  power  of  blood  is  referred  to  in  the  seven- 
teenth chapter  of  Leviticus,  and  developed  in  Christianity 
into  the  eucharistic  sacrifice.  It  is  also  fairly  clearly  rec- 
ognized in  all  bloody  rites  performed  in  the  service  of 
spirits. 

Other  references  can  be  drawn  from  numerous  sources. 
The  marvelous  blood-stains  which  remain  on  hero's  sword 
and  in  haunted  house;  the  practice  of  signing  important 
acts  (such  as  pacts  with  the  devil!)  in  blood;  the  impurity 
of  blood  when  on  the  person ;  all  illustrate  the  general  con- 
ception of  its  extraordinary  properties. 

The  persistence  and  generality  of  such  ideas  point  to 
some  underlying  psychical  fact.  At  first  sight  the  com- 
mon experience  of  nausea  or  fainting  at  the  sight  of  blood 
might  be  regarded  as  the  fundamental  cause,  but  a  little 
consideration  will  show  that  this  is  either  one  of  the  effects 
of  the  cause  we  seek  or  a  vestigial  retro-reminiscence  of 
the  beliefs  on  the  subject  which  dominated  our  forefathers. 

To  the  writer  it  appears  that  the  mere  continuous  juxta- 
position of  blood  with  pain  and  death  in  common  experi- 
ence, extending  through  untold  generations,  is  quite  suffi- 
cient to  account  for  the  effects  and  beliefs  which  have  been 
referred  to,  acting  in  accordance  with  the  laws  of  psychic 
change.  In  minds  which  have  not  been  trained  to  oppose 
the  quasi-mechanical  suggestions  of  revived  memories  by 


9O  THE  MONIST. 

specially  developed  associations  (religious  or  scientific), 
the  percept  of  blood  will .  immediately  call  up  memories  of 
pain  and  death.  These  again  will  be  followed  by  memories 
of  incipient  insensibility  and  fear,  which  will  tend  to  be 
realized  again  in  the  organism  by  a  partial  paralysis  of  the 
motor  centers  etc.,  i.  e.,  the  organism  will  reproduce  as  far 
as  possible  the  state  remembered. 

These  changes,  proceeding  from  a  cause  not  imme- 
diately apparent  to  sense,  are  naturally  ascribed  to  an  ex- 
ternal source,  more  particularly  in  view  of  the  fact  that 
another  person  (such  as  a  wizard)  can  by  insistent  sug- 
gestion (with  or  without  hypnosis)  set  the  train  of  trans- 
formation in  motion. 

Blood  has  a  quite  perceptible  smell  (the  extraordinary 
sensitiveness  of  carnivorous  animals  and  insects  needs  only 
to  be  mentioned  in  support  of  this  fact)  and  a  perception 
of  this  is  sufficient  to  provide  a  basis  for  the  belief  in  pecu- 
liar sanguinary  emanations.  Add  to  this  the  obvious  con- 
nection between  blood  and  vitality,  and  we  have  a  complete 
nexus  of  percepts  which  will  suggest  all  the  magical  ideas 
mentioned,  and  by  the  encouragement  of  such  suggestions 
will  tend  to  realize  the  psychical  counterparts  of  such  mag- 
ical causes. 

Some  modifications  in  this  statement  may  be  conceded 
to  those  who  under  the  vague  name  of  occultists  contend 
that  a  whole  series  of  supernormal  laws  continuously  ope- 
rates on  human  affairs.  Such  will  say  that  all  the  prop- 
erties attributed  to  blood  in  universal  spiritualistic  belief 
are  real,  that  spirits  (shells)  can  absorb  sanguinary  ema- 
nations and  thereby  vitalize  themselves,  etc.  To  them  it 
may  be  said  that  using  the  word  "spirit"  as  equivalent  to 
"idea"  the  difference  is  merely  a  matter  of  terminology. 

HERBERT  CHATLEY. 

T'ANG  SHAN,  NORTH  CHINA,  Oct.  1911. 


AUTOMATISM. 

IN  approaching  a  subject  of  such  an  uncertain  nature,  of 
such  wide  bearing  and  interest  to  humanity,  and  resting 
on  the  much  disputed  border  of  the  unknown,  it  is  only 
with  the  greatest  regard  for  fact  and  approved  hypotheses, 
and  the  utmost  caution  in  reasoning  that  I  have  felt  myself 
at  all  capable  of  developing  it  to  any  conclusion.  The  na- 
ture of  the  subject  forbids  any  actual  proof  by  our  present 
facilities  and  in  no  place  would  I  wish  to  assume  my  own 
infallibility.  While  the  metaphysics  of  the  question  is,  at 
present,  of  no  practical  use  or  bearing,  yet  a  knowledge  of 
the  government  of  our  actions  and  a  conception  of  what 
this  government  and  its  rules  should  be,  I  may  state  to  be 
the  thing  of  highest  utility  and  interest  to  us.  According 
to  Mill,  "no  belief  which  is  contrary  to  the  truth  can  be 
really  useful,"  and  so,  at  least,  there  is  some  excuse,  aside 
from  complete  treatment  of  the  subject,  for  developing  its 
metaphysical  side  before  proceeding  to  that  of  more  im- 
mediate utility — the  educational  and  moral  phases.  Many 
treatises  and  good  have  been  written  upon  this  subject, 
and  many  strong  arguments  pro  and  con  adduced,  but  there 
is  always  a  last  word  to  be  said,  and  the  best  inferences 
and  reasons  have  been  put  to  shame  as  the  truth  has  slowly 
come  to  light. 

No  man  is  so  presumptuous  as  to  assert  that  he  recog- 
nizes all  causes  which  tend  toward  the  production  of  any 
phenomenon,  but  a  faith  that  they  exist  and  are  discover- 
able, is  what  has  led  to  the  present  glory  and  brilliance  of 


92  THE  MONIST. 

science.  Man  wonders  and  is  curious  now  even  as  he  was 
in  the  dim  ages,  but  he  has  learned  one  lesson, — to  investi- 
gate for  natural  causes  instead  of  "explaining  away"  his 
ignorance  by  the  creation  of  supernatural  powers ;  and  the 
answers  which  he  gives  to  the  questions  of  the  universe 
to-day  are  not  mere  placebos  to  console  his  passion  for  an 
answer  and  to  feed  his  emotions,  but  passion  has  been  sup- 
planted by  a  higher  and  more  lasting  emotion;  namely, 
the  desire  for  the  satisfaction  of  reason  with  positive  and 
logically  deduced  knowledge;  and  nothing  more  and  noth- 
ing less  will  suffice. 

In  order  to  conform  to  this  inner  desire  and  all  that  is 
implied  with  it,  it  is  not  necessary  to  exclude  all  belief  and 
remain  purely  agnostic,  but  to  have  that  belief  bounded  and 
governed  by  the  known  facts  of  science  and  its  articles 
determined  by  the  most  plausible  inferences  adducible 
therefrom.  All  men,  no  matter  in  what  age  or  circum- 
stances, have  with  the  greatest  legitimacy  constructed  a 
cosmos  and  not  a  chaos  as  their  picture  of  the  nature  of 
things.  For  do  they  not  see  around  them  at  all  times  direct 
evidence  of  law  and  order  in  the  workings  of  all  material 
forces  ?  And  the  least  of  confirmation  is  a  pillar  to  belief. 

To  develop  here  whatever  system  of  belief  might  be 
entertained  with  the  sanction  of  facts  would  hardly  be 
within  the  confines  of  my  subject,  but  suffice  it  to  say  that 
I  agree  with  Spinoza  who  says  that  "an  appeal  to  the  inter- 
ference of  a  soul  (or  unknown  spiritual  force)  in  order  to 
explain  a  corporeal  state,  is  an  admission  that  we  do  not 
know  its  cause."  I  can  in  no  way  sympathize  with  the 
inert  mind  of  the  Orient  which,  too  drunk  with  sun  and 
plenty,  must  depend  upon  the  spirit  to  fill  the  vacancy  in 
its  knowledge, — a  spirit  about  which  it  has  even  less  of  an 
idea  than  of  the  material  phenomenon  itself.  In  the  ab- 
sence of  knowledge  we  are  only  justified  by  an  inference 
which  we  believe  to  be  in  the  direction  pointed  out  by  facts. 


AUTOMATISM.  93 

Now  the  material  and  its  actions  are  the  only  facts  with 
which  we  are  acquainted.  Science  has  classified  these  facts 
of  experience  and  induced  laws  therefrom  and  in  every 
case  the  fact  has  been  of  a  material  and  causative  nature. 
It  therefore  becomes  our  first  duty  to  attempt  the  reduc- 
tion of  all  phenomena  to  a  physical,  substantive  basis  and 
not,  when  we  have  no  conception  of  the  cause,  to  say  that 
its  nature  is  "spiritual,"  but  courageously  to  assert  our 
ignorance  concerning  it  and  work  with  the  faith  that  it 
may  be  reduced  to  a  natural,  materially  caused  phenom- 
enon. Never  ignorabimus !  I  shall  preserve  this  rule,  and 
work  with  this  end  in  view  in  all  that  follows. 

It  may  satisfy  some  to  ease  their  desire  for  rationality 
with  the  following  statement  of  Haeckel,  but,  however  true, 
it  does  not  make  a  direct  argument  against  the  reason  of 
the  indeterminist,  which  first  of  all  must  be  shown  falla- 
cious before  our  own  can  trust  the  evidence.  Professor 
Haeckel  says,  "As  to  the  question  of  free-will  which  has 
kept  the  world  busy  for  two  thousand  years,  and  which 
has  produced  so  many  books  that  encumber  our  libraries 
and  accumulate  dust  therein, — this  question  also  is  no  more 
than  a  memory.  Of  what  value  are  vague  suggestions 
based  upon  sentiment,  in  comparison  with  scientific  deduc- 
tions ?  The  will  indeed  is  not  an  inert  force.  It  is  a  power 
of  automatic  and  conscious  reaction  which  is  regulative 
and  actively  influential.  But  the  inclinations  that  are  in- 
separable from  life  itself  explain  this  attribute,  and  as  to 
the  mode  of  action  inherent  in  the  will  we  only  consider 
it  free  because,  following  the  abstract  and  dualistic  method 
of  metaphysicians,  we  isolate  this  faculty  from  the  condi- 
tions which  determine  it.  We  have  not,  first  of  all,  to  con- 
sider the  will  separately,  and  then  examine  the  circum- 
stances wherein  it  acts.  The  will  as  given  is  burdened 
with  a  thousand  determinations  which  heredity  has  settled 
upon  it.  And  each  of  its  resolutions  is  an  adaptation  of  its 


94  THE  MONIST. 

pre-existing  inclination  to  actual  circumstances.  The 
strongest  motive  prevails  mechanically  by  virtue  of  the 
laws  which  govern  the  statics  of  emotion.  If  then  the 
merely  abstract  and  verbal  will  appears  free,  the  concrete 
will  is  determined  like  everything  else  in  the  universe." 

To  say  this  in  the  face  of  the  overwhelming  number  of 
scientific  and  unscientific  indeterminists  is  not  enough, 
and  it  is  the  object  of  this  essay  to  adduce  such  reasons  as 
will  lead  to  the  establishment  of  these  statements  as  facts. 
In  doing  so,  let  me  say  that  I  do  not  consider  it  inconsistent 
to  accept  and  reason  from  the  tried  theories  of  science 
which  have  stood  the  test  of  time  and  criticism. 

We  know  that  during  that  comparatively  simple  condi- 
tion of  the  earth,  before  the  Laurentian  age  and  the  pri- 
mordial deposits,  a  simple  organic  unit  was  produced. 
Bernard,  who  has  made  the  cell  his  life-study,  has  reduced 
the  cell,  which  had  been  formerly  considered  the  unit  of 
structure,  to  what  he  terms  the  "chromidial  unit,"  a  more 
elementary  organic  structure,  having  as  definite  a  mor- 
phological significance  in  its  own  way  as  the  cell.  It  can 
be  claimed  therefore  that  some  such  unit  produced  all  the 
pre-cellular  organisms  which  built  up,  among  other  less 
successful  organisms,  the  famous  cell  with  which  biol- 
ogists usually  start  their  record  of  life.  Not  only  was  the 
cell  a  highly  efficient  organism  in  itself,  as  is  shown  by  the 
fact  that  so  many  unicellular  organisms  exist  to-day,  but 
it  had  the  power  of  multiplying  indefinitely  and  forming 
colonies,  which  colonies  have  become  organisms  specialized 
to  numberless  more  and  ever  more  complicated  environ- 
ments. For  the  specialization  of  a  large  colony  of  cells 
as  a  whole  must  necessarily  be  able  to  reach  a  level  of  com- 
plexity higher  than  that  to  which  any  single  cell  could 
possibly  attain.  So  thus  life  was  raised  from  one  level  of 
complexity  to  a  higher  one,  and  it  is  by  comparatively  little 
reasoning  that  we  reach  the  age  of  man. 


AUTOMATISM.  95 

Now  in  the  simple  stage  of  the  earth's  history  and  even 
later  in  the  postcellular  age,  it  is  acknowledged  that  all 
phenomena  obeyed  explicitly  the  omnipotent,  omnipresent 
law  of  cause-effect.  The  actions  of  the  ameba  are  nothing 
but  the  simplest  of  reflexes  from  external  stimuli  and 
this  same  action  is  admitted  to  continue  up  to  the  lower 
vertebrates.  All  those  who  have  expounded  the  doctrine 
of  free  will  have,  therefore,  consciously  or  unconsciously, 
stated  that  at  some  unknown  instant  of  time  in  the  slow, 
gradual  evolution  of  organic  life,  and  also  in  the  growth  of 
the  embryo  or  early  life  of  the  infant,  the  animal  has 
ceased  to  act  according  to  the  natural  laws  of  its  previous 
action  and  a  force  has  crept  into  a  universe  which  em- 
braces all  space,  which  is  able  to  produce  material  phe- 
nomena on  its  own  account  and  aside  from  the  law  that 
all  motion  possesses  a  cause  of  which  it  is  the  direct  effect. 
Is  it  not  absurd  to  hold  that  the  action  of  a  few  of  the 
higher  animals  are  not  caused  and  so  proceed  by  "their 
own  virtue?"  Is  this  not  exactly  how  primitive  man  "ex- 
plained away"  any  phenomenon  of  the  cause  of  which  he 
was  ignorant?  How  unreasonable  it  is  when  we  realize 
the  complex  nature  of  the  subject  of  our  study  and  the 
complex  environment  upon  which  he  must  react,  to  infer 
that  his  action  is  not  a  more  complex  one  working  by  the 
same  rules  as  his  simpler  action  did  in  past  ages  at  the 
time  of  his  humble  origin.  It  is  a  case  of  realizing  that  a 
million  phenomena  whose  cause  is  known  to  reside  in  a 
certain  law,  surround  one  phenomenon, — that  of  the  ac- 
tion of  the  higher  animals,  the  complexity  of  which  has 
baffled  our  investigation,  and  therefore  that  we  do  not 
assign  this  one  to  law,  but  label  it  a  causeless  phenomenon 
the  action  of  which  is  based  upon  the  "virtue  of  the  will." 
It  is  the  insignia  and  confession  of  the  lack  of  knowledge 
and  the  lack  of  inductive  reasoning  power  of  a  great  num- 
ber of  our  professed  scientific  thinkers.  They  should  ob- 


96  THE  MONIST. 

serve  their  rule,  namely,  that  if  the  law  applies  in  a  thousand 
cases  the  probability  is  a  thousand  to  one  that  it  will  apply 
in  the  thousand  and  first  case. 

There  is  also  another  serious  difficulty  which  presents 
itself  to  the  exponents  of  free  will,  and  as  yet  none  have 
replied  successfully  to  Professor  Clifford  who  I  believe 
was  the  first  to  discover  it.  In  extract  it  is  this :  the  will, 
in  being  pure  and  uninfluenced  in  its  choice  or  production 
of  a  material  phenomenon,  and  therefore  free,  as  they  say, 
must,  in  not  being  governed  according  to  cause-effect,  in- 
fluence matter  through  the  immaterial ;  and  aside  from  the 
fact  that  the  existence  of  the  immaterial  is  inconceivable, 
otherwise  than  that  matter  should  be  governed  by  any- 
thing but  surrounding  matter  is  also  inconceivable,  and 
both  are  therefore  highly  improbable.  The  conclusion 
therefore  is  inevitable  that  the  will  is  a  physical  manifesta- 
tion and  governed  by  the  laws  of  physics. 

No  real  boundary  exists  between  the  unconscious  in- 
voluntary actions  of  instinct  born  in  us  or  of  habits  formed, 
and  the  subconscious  "quasi-voluntary"  action  of  brushing 
the  dust  off  one's  sleeve  during  a  conversation,  or  between 
the  subconscious  and  more  complex  reactions  in  full  con- 
sciousness. It  is  a  known  fact  that  when  the  higher  forms 
of  memory  appear  in  animal  life,  a  fuller  and  more  com- 
plete consciousness  exists.  And  this  is  necessarily  the  case, 
for  in  order  to  obtain  the  more  complex  reactions  of  the 
higher  animals,  it  is  necessary  that  a  greater  memory  of 
the  results  of  actions  be  had  and  so  a  fuller  consciousness 
for  the  revolving  of  the  many  memories  to  obtain  the  most 
favorable  idea  of  the  would-be  consequence  and  so  its  en- 
actment. For  the  most  favorable  memory  or  idea  of  the 
consequences  of  actions  determines  our  choice,  on  account 
of  the  self-instinct  necessitated  by  the  law  of  natural  selec- 
tion and  whatever  social  education  we  have  had. 

Most  indeterminists,  believing  that  ab  extra  the  mental 


AUTOMATISM.  97 

and  physical  processes  go  along  on  two  parallel  platforms 
—the  mental  activity  opposite  the  corresponding  physical 
activity — are  confronted  by  this  argument:  Since  we  are 
reasoning  beings,  there  is  a  chain  of  mental  facts  be- 
tween the  incoming  and  a  motor  action,  and  so  there  is  a 
complete  chain  of  physical  facts  sufficient  to  produce  the 
action ;  for  before  and  along  with  the  mental  act  of  willing 
there  is  a  parallel  brain  action  which  is  caused  and  which 
causes  the  motor  action.  There  is  then  no  need  for  the 
parallel  mental  process  theory,  for  by  its  parallelistic  nature 
it  destroys  our  incapacity  for  accounting  for  all  phenomena 
physically,  which  incapacity  caused  its  creation  to  "explain 
away"  certain  of  the  higher  animal  actions.  The  word 
mental  should  signify  only  in  consciousness. 

Again,  how  can  pure  abstract  "will"  influence  material 
action  ?  Allowing  that  not  only  to  us  but  in  abstract  that 
"mental"  processes  intervene  between  the  sensation  and 
motor  action,  how  is  one  to  get  across  from  the  physical 
to  the  mental  platform  and  then  back  onto  the  physical 
again?  This  detour,  made  by  metaphysicians  on  account 
of  ignorance,  leads  me  to  doubt  the  existence  of  the  "men- 
tal," immaterial  platform.  I  fail  to  see  the  relation  between 
will  and  motion  by  which  one  can  cause  the  other,  unless 
"will"  and  "mind"  are  inherent  in  it,  i.  e.,  a  manifestation 
of  molecular  or  molar  motion  and  therefore  governed  ac- 
cording to  cause-effect  and  not  free.  The  following  dia- 
gram will  illustrate  the  point: 


If  it  be  asserted  that  the  psychical  is  inherent  in  in- 
organic nature,  I  have  nothing  to  say,  for  molecular, 
atomic,  and  ionic  structure  is  too  little  known ;  but  I  believe 


98  THE  MONIST. 

that  it  is  inherent  only  in  the  sense  that  material  compo- 
sition is  such  that  it  could  produce  (by  combinations  and 
processes  unknown)  conscious  life.  It  has  been  said  that 
consciousness  as  a  form  of  motion  is  inconceivable,  but  ad- 
mitting its  truth  I  do  not  consider  it  a  valid  argument 
against  materialism,  for  what  kind  of  an  idea  of  conscious- 
ness can  we  have  when  consciousness  can  only  be  the  sub- 
ject and  never  the  object,  as  we  are  contained  in  it? 

So  in  conclusion  on  the  physical  facts  of  the  case,  the 
argument  may  be  summed  up  in  these  words :  In  our  devel- 
opment from  the  first  transitional  organic  form  to  the  cell 
and  on  through  the  gastraedic  and  invertebrate  age  our 
condition  has  resembled  that  of  the  monera,  amoeba,  pla- 
tode,  and  up  to  the  lower  vertebrates,  whose  action  is  so 
simple  that  it  is  readily  admitted  to  be  mechanical.  But 
when  we  come  to  higher  vertebrates  and  promammals, 
which  we  resembled  at  a  more  recent  period,  their  constitu- 
tion and  action  has  become  so  complex  that  we  must  aban- 
don consistency  and  say :  because  we  see  no  cause  of  their 
actions  is  there  none?  No,  reason  forbids.  Upon  the 
fertilization  of  the  ovum  and  the  formation  of  the  stem- 
cell  the  life  of  a  human  individual  begins.  This  is  a  me- 
chanical process  as  is  the  development  of  the  embryo;  the 
early  life  of  the  infant  is  a  combination  of  instinct  and 
reflex  action — purely  mechanical.  But  after  the  plastic 
brain  substance  of  the  infant  has  received  and  held  many 
impressions  from  the  outside  world  he  is  equipped  for  a 
more  complex  reaction  against  it,  and  since  many  pro- 
fessed scientists  neither  realize  what  his  memories  are  nor 
see  how  the  most  favorable  one  coupled  with  the  self-pres- 
ervation instinct  sets  forth  his  action,  so  they  assign  the  ac- 
tion to  his  pure  will  to  do  it  and  nothing  else.  Let  us  use 
reason  in  this  case.  If  the  action  were  considered  dynam- 
ically and  an  investigation  made  of  its  exact  molecular 
cause  and  its  force  it  would  be  an  operation  among  those 


AUTOMATISM.  99 

physiological  infinitesimals  which  present  calculation  must 
neglect  but  to  which  faith  must  grant  an  existence.  The 
removal  of  the  cerebral  hemisphere  reduces  all  action  to 
a  pure  and  simple  automatic  nature  and  no  one  has  had 
the  opportunity,  knowledge  or  facilities  to  watch  and  trace 
the  origin  of  the  so-called  voluntary  actions  in  the  myste- 
rious mazes  of  the  frontal  brain.  It  remains  for  us  but  to 
wait  until  methods  are  so  perfected  and  until  men,  realizing 
that  knowledge  is  power,  educate  themselves  unhesitatingly 
to  investigate  with  a  view  towards  their  high  aim,  upon 
the  highest  form  of  living  subject  obtainable,  for  a  con- 
firmation of  those  inferences  we  have  deemed  reasonable. 
"The  higher  we  ascend  in  the  vertebrate  series  toward 
man,"  says  Dr.  Carpenter,  "the  more  evident  does  it  become 
that  the  ordinary  course  of  action  is  determined  rather  by 
the  direction  given  through  the  cerebrum  to  the  workings 
of  the  automatic  mechanism  than  by  its  (the  cerebrum's) 
ow-n  unconscious  action."  In  other  words,  by  reason  rather 
than  by  instinct.  And  in  man  we  find  that  everything  is 
to  be  learned  by  experience,  save  what  is  imperatively  re- 
quired for  the  maintenance  of  life — such  as  the  rhythmical 
contractions  of  the  heart,  the  peristaltic  movements  of  the 
alimentary  canal,  the  acts  of  swallowing  and  respiration 
and  the  like.  It  has  already  been  mentioned  that  memory 
is  the  great  prerequisite  for  all  "voluntary"  action,  and  it 
it  is  also  known  that  the  actions  of  the  human  embryo  are 
not  of  that  sort  until 

"Nature  whose  heedless  might 
Casts  like  some  shipwrecked  sailor,  the  poor  babe, 
Naked  and  bleating  on  the  shores  of  light." 

From  that  instant  the  memory  is  in  process  of  formation, 
the  conscious  personality  begins,  habit  adds  to  the  role 
of  the  involuntary  centers,  which  previously  possessed  only 
instinct,  and  the  infant  can  thus  react  more  perfectly  upon 
complex  conditions  and  exert  less  effort  in  the  performance 


IOO  THE  MONIST. 

of  simple  and  necessarily  repeated  actions,  for  their  per- 
formance has  become  habitual  and  subconscious.  Thus  he 
is  able  to  direct  his  higher  activities  to  the  more  difficult 
phases  of  his  being — to  this  end  has  the  law  of  natural 
selection,  joined  with  variation,  ever  worked  in  the  mental 
field.  This  is  the  pregnant  fact  upon  which  I  shall  build 
my  argument  from  the  mental  side  of  the  question. 

As  shown  under  hypnosis,  an  impression  of  every  ex- 
perience, of  the  sight  of  every  performance  of  others,  of 
the  result  of  every  action,  is  indelibly  recorded  in  the 
brain,  whether  it  ever  be  brought  into  consciousness  or 
not.  We  therefore  have  for  our  use  the  knowledge  of  the 
result  of  a  thousand  actions,  whether  it  be  of  the  tongue 
or  of  the  hand.  Now  we  also  possess  from  heredity  the 
overwhelming  instinct  of  self-preservation  and  its  brother, 
the  desire  for  what  is  productive  of  the  greatest  happiness 
to  us.  The  following  mental  process  is  easily  discernible 
by  introspection:  a  condition  arises  in  the  environment 
necessitating  a  reaction;  the  memory  arises  of  certain  re- 
sults upon  the  individual  of  an  action  of  his  own  or  of 
some  one  else ;  if  it  be  a  favorable  result  his  interest  in  the 
possible  action  is  aroused  and  his  attention  is  then  directed 
toward  it;  the  same  occurs  (from  association  of  ideas  in 
the  memory)  to  four  or  five  (taking  an  extreme  case  of 
indecision)  ideas  of  possible  action;  the  attention  is  di- 
rected then  from  one  to  the  other  and  a  comparison  of 
them  is  made  according  to  the  individual's  belief  m  the 
probable  nature  of  their  results;  one  appears  more  favor- 
able to  his  happiness  and  welfare  than  the  others,  where- 
upon it  is  acted  out.  Thus  truly  considering  the  necessity 
of  memory,  Plato  has  reason  to  name  it  a  great  and  mighty 
goddess.  If  it  were  not  for  this  cause-effect  mental  process, 
I  would  fear  greatly  for  the  happiness  and  interests  of  the 
individual,  if  there  could  be  individual  life  without  it.  One 
of  the  potent  factors  in  causing  such  a  strenuous  advocacy 


AUTOMATISM.  IOI 

of  free-will  is  the  pride  and  vanity  of  man  in  himself  and 
his  powers.  But  how  often  has  that  pride  been  humbled 
and  how  often  must  it  be  in  the  future  when  such  facts 
as  his  low  origin  or  his  unlikeness  to  the  image  of  God 
are  forced  upon  his  realization! 

The  power  of  suggestion  and  association  of  idea  with 
idea,  such  as  I  experience  as  I  sit  here  writing,  must  also 
be  thoroughly  recognized  and  considered  before  any  valid- 
ity, let  alone  prestige,  can  be  given  to  the  statements  of  an 
indeterminist.  The  previous  paragraph  has  shown  the 
method  of  the  objective  or  higher  faculties  in  arriving  at 
a  conclusion  for  action,  but  the  memory,  or  what  has  been 
termed  the  unconscious,  subjective  mind  is  always  amen- 
able to  suggestion  and  will  catch  the  objective  faculties 
off  their  guard  if  possible.  A  friend  related  an  excellent 
example  of  this  some  days  ago:  A  young  man  who  had 
determined  to  stop  drinking  was  invited  to  step  into  a 
saloon  and  have  a  glass.  He  was  prepared  for  this  and 
the  suggestion  brought  up  the  reply  no.  A  few  days  later 
an  old  school  friend  met  him  and  said,  "Let's  go  in  and 
sit  down  and  talk  over  old  times."  He  went  in  and  it  is 
unnecessary  to  say,  succumbed.  Taking  up  the  association 
of  memories  or  ideas,  let  me  ask  the  free-will  exponents 
if  the  "chance"  were  at  all  probable,  of  my  turning  ten 
minutes  ago  to  the  beginning  of  this  paragraph  and  writ- 
ing the  word  the  with  which  to  start  this  paragraph,  the 
idea  of  what  I  have  just  written  springing  spontaneously 
from  my  brain  ?  I  also  ask  them  to  exercise  their  powers 
of  introspection  until  they  have  gained  proficiency  enough 
to  trace  back  why  they  did  this  or  thought  that  the  moment 
before,  winding  the  string  (of  cause-effect)  as  they  go 
along  and  reach,  say,  their  experience  an  hour  ago.  My 
opponents  paradoxically  admit  that  they  are  not  reasoning 
men,  for  they  say  they  do  just  as  their  "free  will"  pleases 
and,  although  moral  men,  are  not  governed  by  duty,  re- 


IO2  THE  MONIST. 

sponsibility,  or  fear  of  consequences.  Freedom  consists 
of  a  recognition  of  facts  and  a  self-government  according 
to  them;  bondage,  of  a  struggle  against  them.  I  have  al- 
ready determined  what  pleases  us, — namely  that  of  which 
the  consequences  are  productive  of  our  happiness  and  well- 
being.  And  the  proud  "free-willers,"  I  believe,  have  some 
hedonists  in  their  ranks  who  will  acknowledge  what  pleases 
them,  so  their  acts  being  governed  by  that,  they  prove 
themselves  traitors  to  the  cause.  Many  people  may  become 
indeterminists  and  reach  that  abnormal  state  of  mind  in 
which  they  can  trust  themselves  to  a  universe  where  law 
and  lawlessness  interchange  indiscriminately,  but  I  con- 
fess myself  unable  to  reach  that  Nirvana. 

Our  own  immediate  mental  experience,  therefore,  has 
shown  that  we  are  no  exception  to  the  rule  (in  that 
we  realize  the  mental  antecedent — the  why  of  our  pur- 
pose) and  they  are  as  worthy  of  confidence,  according  to 
Dr.  Carpenter,  as  are  "deductions  drawn  from  phenomena 
outside  ourselves,  which  we  can  only  rightfully  interpret 
on  the  basis  afforded  by  those  very  experiences,  the  test 
of  the  validity  of  such  interpretation  being  furnished  by 
their  conformity  to  our  other  immediate  experiences. "  It 
is  well  known  that  the  hemisphereless  frog  or  pigeon  acts 
automatically  when  any  thing  directly  stimulating  is  ad- 
ministered, but  remains  perfectly  passive  until  then.  The 
hemispheres,  therefore,  are  the  seats  of  higher  conscious- 
ness wherein  a  more  complex  reaction  is  aroused  from 
more  distant  and  delicate  stimuli  from  without — after  the 
formation  of  the  memory  within — but  not  less  automatic 
action.  Our  consciousness  of  effort  arises  from  the  many 
and  intricate  processes  of  conscious  reasoning,  judgment, 
etc.,  before  arriving  at  a  decision  or  choice,  and  is  accom- 
panied by  the  feeling  of  effort  arising  from  muscular  move- 
ment. It  has  been  often  urged  that,  since  neurosis  can 
give  rise  to  psychosis,  it  is  surely  quite  accordant  with  the 


AUTOMATISM.  103 

fundamental  principle  of  interaction  to  affirm  that  con- 
versely, psychosis  can  give  rise  to  neurosis,  just  as  the 
electricity  generated  in  a  voltaic  battery  by  chemical  change 
can  itself  produce  chemical  change.  I  quite  agree — the 
psychosis  being  neurosis  consciously  felt.  The  neurosis 
afferently  causes  psychosis,  i.  e.,  causes  will;  the  psy- 
chosis efferently  (in  regard  to  the  ego)  causes  neurosis 
and  bodily  motion.  He  simply  affirms  the  chain  of  cause- 
effect  and  the  law  of  the  conservation  of  energy. 

In  fact,  unless  combination  of  memories  were  used  to 
determine  our  actions  and  memory  be  but  a  rudiment,  or 
else  that  memory  is  used  for  that  purpose  now,  I  can  see 
no  object  past  or  present  toward  which  it  would  be  of 
utility.  Darwin  and  his  followers  have  shown  that  an 
animal  possesses  a  function  because  it  was  either  of  use 
to  its  ancestors  or  to  itself.  Therefore  since  memory 
would  be  useless  unless  it  helped  and  guided  our  actions 
we  must  concede  that  it  does ;  and  we  can  also  conclude  that 
where  animals  acted  in  accordance  with  a  more  perfect 
memory  (arising  from  variation)  their  actions  were  more 
in  accordance  with  the  requirements  of  nature  and  they 
more  fit  to  live.  Thus  natural  selection  has  produced  this, 
as  well  as  all  other  necessary  functions.  Who  would  at- 
tempt an  explanation  of  the  molecular  causes  of  those 
imaginary  actions  in  dreams?  Memory  is  involved  here 
but  the  channels  through  which  we  come  to  those  imagina- 
tions are  so  subconscious  as  to  baffle  all  introspection;  yet 
there  is  no  manifestation  of  will  in  them  and  it  is  compara- 
tively easy  to  see  the  by-cause  of  conscious  volitions. 

Under  hypnotism  the  will  or  judgment  is  unconscious. 
The  man  is  under  the  complete  control  of  the  present  sug- 
gestion. Now  we  see  that  it  is  not  a  very  beneficial  reac- 
tion when  no  distinction  can  be  made  between  the  false  and 
true,  right  and  wrong,  etc.  And  thus  natural  selection 
gave  rise  to  the  will — judgment  (comparison  of  memories) 


IO4  THE  MONIST. 

coupled  with  action.  The  comparison  was  and  is  necessary 
for  existence  by  a  high  reaction  even  as  the  hemispheres 
were  and  are  necessary  to  a  reaction  from  more  distant 
and  delicate  stimuli.  The  hemisphereless  frog  and  the 
hypnotized  man  are  admitted  automatons  but  when  there 
were  neither  of  these  conditions  and  the  reaction  was  com- 
plex— from  revolving  of  memories  and  comparison  of  them, 
and  from  distant  stimuli  they  were  thought  uncaused  as  we 
had  no  knowledge  or  perception  of  them.  Now  that  we 
see  the  why,  we  realize  that  automatic  nature  in  the  ab- 
sence of  hypnoses  or  presence  of  the  hemispheres  as  well  as 
in  the  opposite  conditions. 

On  the  freedom  of  choice  this  is  the  sole  reply  which 
I  find  from  the  indeterministic  pen.  "And  yet  on  the 
deterministic  doctrine,  if  I  am  attracted  by  the  temptation 
of  an  immediate  but  immoral  pleasure,  and  am  deterred 
from  it  either  by  a  sense  of  duty  or  by  the  fear  of  the 
remote  consequences  of  the  sin,  I  have  no  more  'choice* 
as  to  the  course  I  shall  take  than  has  the  piece  of  iron  that 
is  attracted  in  opposite  directions  by  two  unequal  equi- 
distant magnets.  Now  my  contention  is  not  merely  that 
I  have  a  choice,  but  that  the  very  existence  of  an  idea  that 
can  be  derived  from  no  other  source  than  human  experi- 
ence, confirms  that  effect."  I  believe  Dr.  Carpenter  per- 
fectly justified  in  making  this  statement.  As  to  the  person 
it  is  a  choice  (at  the  moment  he  does  not  figure  out  all 
reasons  or  causes,  they  being  subconscious),  but  the 
"choice,"  not  to  us  but  abstractly,  is  determined  and  non- 
existent. The  fact  that  all  experience  shows  that  motives 
which  may  exert  a  preponderating  influence  at  one  mo- 
ment, are  comparatively  powerless  at  another,  and  that, 
on  the  other  hand,  motives  whose  influence  at  one  moment 
is  scarcely  felt,  may  come  to  acquire  a  force  that  makes 
them  far  outweigh  those  which  at  first  overbalanced  them, 
shows  that,  although  we  do  not  know  what  is  really  the 


AUTOMATISM.  10$ 

best  decision,  if  we  can  be  made  to  believe  that  a  certain 
one  is  (by  any  means  whatever)  better,  that  is  the  one 
which  the  self-instinct,  or  whatever  social  education  we 
have  had,  embodies  with  the  proper  action.  Indeterminism 
confesses  its  inability  to  trace  anything  behind  the  will  or 
existing  before  it  which  is  in  any  way  connected  with  it; 
determinism  confesses  that  it  sees  and  also  consciously  ex- 
periences (and  what  our  consciousness  tells  us  is  the  surest 
reality  to  us)  a  phenomenon  existing  before  it  in  time  and 
determinedly  related  to  it.  In  other  words,  the  will  is  not 
a  spontaneous  and  independent  thing  leaning  only  against 
itself. 

Santayana  says,  "Mankind  and  all  its  works  are  un- 
deniably subject  to  gravity  and  to  the  law  of  projectiles; 
yet  what  is  true  of  these  phenomena  in  bulk  seems  to  a 
superficial  observation  not  to  be  true  of  them  in  detail, 
and  a  person  may  imagine  that  he  subverts  all  the  laws 
of  physics  whenever  he  wags  his  tongue,  only  in  inorganic 
matter  is  the  ruling  of  mechanism  open  to  human  inspec- 
tion ;  here  changes  may  be  seen  to  be  proportionate  to  the 
elements  and  situation  in  which  they  occur.  . .  .  Physics 
cannot  account  for  that  minute  motion  and  pullulation  of 
the  earth's  crust  of  which  human  affairs  are  a  portion. 
Human  affairs  have  to  be  surveyed  under  the  categories 
lying  closer  to  those  employed  in  memory  and  legend.  . .  . 
That  this  gulf  is  apparent  only,  being  due  to  inadequacy 
and  confusion  in  human  perception  rather  than  to  inco- 
herence in  things,  is  a  speculative  conviction  altogether 
trustworthy ....  Now  the  human  senses  are  not  at  all  fitted 
to  represent  an  organism  on  the  scale  of  the  human  body. 
They  catch  its  idle  gestures  but  not  the  inner  processes 
which  control  its  action.  The  senses  are  immeasurably  too 
gross.  What  to  them  is  a  minimum  visibile,  a  just  per- 
ceptible atom,  is  in  the  body's  structure,  very  likely,  a 
system  of  worlds,  the  inner  catclysms  of  which  count  in 


106  THE  MONIST. 

producing  that  so-called  atom's  behaviour  and  endowing 
it  with  affinities  apparently  miraculous.  What  must  the 
seed  of  animals  contain,  for  instance,  to  be  the  ground, 
as  it  notoriously  is,  for  every  physical  and  moral  property 
of  the  offspring?.  . .  .  Any  one  who  can  at  all  catch  the 
drift  of  experience — moral  no  less  than  spiritual — must 
feel  that  mechanism  rules  the  whole  world." 

According  to  Spinoza,  that  masterful  combination  of 
reason  and  intuitional  insight,  "A  thing  is  said  to  be  free 
(liber a)  which  exists  by  the  mere  necessity  of  its  own 
nature,  and  is  determined  in  its  actions  by  itself  alone." 
If,  then,  men  can  attribute  no  reason  for  the  willing  of 
anything  beyond  the  immediate  cause,  then  the  will  is  in- 
finite beyond  that  cause ;  then  the  will  is  equal  in  power  to 
God,  in  that  He  would  have  no  control  thereover  and  all 
the  burden  and  responsibility  of  a  choice,  which  may  affect 
the  lives  of  many  men,  is  placed  upon  this  will,  infinite 
in  its  nature  yet  limited  in  its  knowledge.  It  is  not  just  nor 
right  that  God  should  place  such  responsibility  in  the  un- 
governed  hands  of  ignorance.  As  God  is  just  and  right- 
eous it  follows  "from  these  premises  then,  that  men  think 
themselves  free  inasmuch  as  they  are  conscious  of  their 
volitions  and  desires,  and,  as  they  are  ignorant  of  the 
causes  by  which  they  are  led  to  wish  and  desire,  they  do 
not  even  dream  of  their  existence."  It  is  then  concluded 
(Prop.  48,  Part  II)  "There  is  in  no  mind  absolute  or  free 
will,  but  the  mind  is  determined  for  this  or  that  by  a  cause 
which  is  determined  in  its  turn  by  another  cause,  and  this 
one  again  by  another,  and  so  on  to  infinity.  Proof. — The 
mind  is  a  fixed  and  determined  mode  of  thinking  and 
therefore  cannot  be  the  free  cause  of  its  actions.  It  cannot 
have  the  absolute  faculty  of  willing  or  unwilling,  but  in 
willing  this  or  that,  it  must  be  determined  from  an  infinite 
line  of  causation." 

Dr.  James  says  in  one  of  his  essays,  "The  sting  of  the 


AUTOMATISM.  IO7 

word  'chance'  seems  to  lie  in  the  assumption  that  it  means 
something  positive,  and  that  if  anything  happens  by  chance 
it  must  needs  be  something  of  an  intrinsically  irrational 
and  preposterous  sort."  But  I  confess  I  can  not  see  that 
unless  chance  is  governed  (or  as  he  says,  "needs  be,")  by 
reason  or  law  (a  contradiction  in  itself)  how  the  result  of 
the  comparatively  few  higher  animal  actions  of  the  future 
could  be  anything  but  "irrational  or  preposterous."  It  is 
a  case  of  to  be  or  not  to  be.  If  "chance"  is  to  be  governed 
by  reason  and  by  law  we  may  expect  the  world  to  continue 
a  part  of  a  universe  in  the  future  and  if  it  is  not,  that  it  will 
become  participant  in  a  nulliverse.  Regret  for  our  past 
actions  and  therefore  the  wish  that  something  might  be 
otherwise  takes  place  in  every  passing  hour  and  is  but  a 
confession  that  had  we  been  wise  enough  our  act  would  not 
have  occasioned  regret  as  it  would  have  been  governed  by 
that  wisdom. 

The  distinct  purposive  intervention  of  the  self-conscious 
ego  is  what  should  be  designated  as  will,  though  the  pur- 
pose and  intervention  be  caused;  it  is  purely  voluntary  to 
us  and  gives  no  feeling  of  oppression  although  in  the  true 
sense  not  "will."  Therefore  to  say  that  you  cannot  per- 
form will  as  I  have  re-defined  it  is  untrue,  for  the  memories 
and  instincts — caused  causes  of  the  will,  are  a  part  and 
contained  in  yourself,  i.  e.,  to  you  the  act  is  will.  From  a 
point  of  view  outside  of  the  self  the  ego  is  not  responsible, 
but  you  are  to  yourself  since  the  will  is  responsible  for  its 
conduct  to  the  memories  and  instincts — the  basis  of  the 
personality.  Yes,  and  the  responsibility  is  exactly  fulfilled. 

I  can  do  no  better  than  conclude  my  argument  from 
the  mental  point  of  view  with  an  illustration  from  the 
thoughtful  pen  of  Thomas  Huxley :  "Suppose  that  an  adult 
man,  in  the  full  rigor  of  his  faculties,  could  be  suddenly 
placed  in  the  world,  as  Adam  is  said  to  have  been,  and 
then  left  to  do  as  he  best  might.  How  long  would  he  be 


IO8  THE  MONIST. 

left  uneducated?  Not  five  minutes.  Nature  would  begin 
to  teach  him,  through  the  eye,  the  ear,  the  touch,  the 
properties  of  objects.  Pain  and  pleasure  would  be  at  his 
elbow  telling  him  to  do  this  and  avoid  that;  and  by  slow 
degrees  the  man  would  receive  an  education  which,  if  nar- 
row, would  be  thorough,  real,  and  adequate  to  his  circum- 
stances, though  there  would  be  no  extras  and  very  few 
accomplishments.  And  if  to  this  solitary  man  entered  a 
second  Adam,  or,  better  still,  an  Eve,  a  new  and  greater 
world,  that  of  social  and  moral  phenomena,  would  be  re- 
vealed. Joys  and  woes,  compared  with  which  all  others 
might  seem  but  faint  shadows,  would  spring  from  the 
new  relations.  Happiness  and  sorrow  would  take  the 
place  of  the  coarser  monitors,  pleasure  and  pain;  but  con- 
duct would  still  be  shaped  by  the  observation  of  the  nat- 
ural consequences  of  actions;  or,  in  other  words,  by  the 
laws  of  the  nature  of  man.  Nor  should  I  speak  of  this 
process  of  education  as  past,  for  any  one,  be  he  old  as  he 
may.  For  every  man  the  world  is  as  fresh  as  it  was  the 
first  day,  and  as  full  of  untold  novelties  for  him  who  has 
eyes  to  see  them.  And  nature  is  still  continuing  her  patient 
education  of  us  in  that  great  university,  the  universe,  of 
which  we  are  all  members,  nature  having  no  Test-Acts. 
Those  who  take  honors  in  nature's  university,  who  learn 
the  laws  which  govern  men  and  things  and  obey  them,  are 
the  really  great  and  successful  men  in  this  world.  The 
great  mass  of  mankind  are  the  Toll/  who  pick  up  just 
enough  to  get  through  without  much  discredit." 

I  have  quoted  this  at  length  because  it  so  admirably 
conveys  the  meaning  which  I  have  tried  to  express  in 
other  words,  and  because  it  contains  the  foundation  of  my 
argument  from  the  moral  side  of  the  question  which  is 
about  to  follow.  In  this  domain  the  exponents  of  free  will 
have  considered  themselves  least  needful  of  defence,  but, 
as  yet,  I  have  not  come  upon  any  elucidation  of  this  side 


AUTOMATISM.  ICX) 

of  the  question  which  was  exactly  satisfactory  to  my  de- 
mands. Either  we  are  wrong  when  we  blame,  or  God  is 
immoral,  and  I  greatly  suspect  that  the  fault  is  to  be  found 
in  our  lack  of  true  moral  comprehension,  rather  than  in 
God.  It  then  becomes  my  duty  to  whitewash  the  Devil, 
although  to  compel  him  to  keep  indoors  is  the  work  of  the 
centuries. 

Going  to  the  foundations  of  morality  must  necessarily 
give  us  a  truer  conception  of  the  import  of  things,  and  must 
also  lead,  by  way  of  our  determinism,  to  a  rational,  opti- 
mistic, trusting  conception  of  the  universe  if  that  doctrine 
is  to  be  entertained  by  us  for  one  moment.  Before  the 
advent  of  man,  it  is  easily  seen  that  nothing  was  moral  or 
immoral,  for  those  terms  are  merely  relative  to  our  mode 
of  thinking  and  arose  with  it.  Nothing  therefore  is  within 
itself  bad  or  good  and  the  words  signify  only  the  fulfillment 
of  the  demands  of  our  nature  upon  phenomena  or  the  lack  of 
it.  That  which  does  not  acquiesce  to  our  demands  is  called 
bad  or  evil  and  if  it  is  shown  that  our  demands  are  the 
result  of  comprehensive  reasoning,  i.  e.,  that  we  can  see 
to  \vhat  end  the  action  or  being  is  directed,  and  that  it  is 
evil  (detrimental  to  happiness  and  well-being  of  men)  then 
we  have  a  right  to  a  pessimism  toward  that  universe  which 
would  produce  good  and  evil  in  motley  alternation.  It 
therefore  devolves  upon  us  here  to  prove  that  the  tendency 
of  all  phenomena  is  that  which  would  secure  the  approba- 
tion of  our  moral  nature  if  we  could  realize  their  end.  Of 
course  we  can  conceive  what  would  be  to  us  a  perfect  uni- 
verse where  all  pain  and  evil  had  a  good  in  its  place,  but  I 
think  we  can  not  censure  the  scheme  or  entertain  a  pes- 
simism if  we  find  that  all  that  is  not  good  is  productive  of 
good,  regardless  of  the  conscious  experience  of  the  indi- 
vidual through  whose  sufTering  good  is  to  be  realized. 
Darwin  truly  states  that  no  species  or  individual  is  perfect 
for  its  reaction  upon  its  environment  (whether  of  the  com- 


IIO  THE  MONIST. 

plex  nature  or  of  the  continual  change  of  the  latter)  and 
Hoffding  perceives  in  his  "critical"  realism  the  never  end- 
ing progress  of  life  toward  that  perfection.  Man's  becom- 
ing a  social  animal  has  raised  the  complexity  of  his  en- 
vironment a  thousandfold,  both  in  relation  to  the  acts  and 
thoughts  of  other  men,  and  in  the  increased  menace  of  dis- 
ease. Now  although  not  so  potent  a  factor  as  it  was  thought 
at  first,  the  law  of  the  natural  selection  of  variant  forms, 
cruel  in  itself,  has  been  the  sole  means  toward  that  good 
end,  our  mind.  She  selected  those  who  gained  and  re- 
tained from  dear  experience  (a  seeming  evil)  the  requisite 
knowledge.  Although  the  weaklings  and  the  deficients 
may  have  been  fostered  by  an  unexacting  environment 
and  the  more  fit  cut  off  by  accident,  yet,  in  the  first  case, 
if  the  environment  remained  and  nothing  stepped  in  to 
improve  the  unfortunates  and  they  generated  degenerates 
which  were  still  fostered  by  easy  surroundings,  the  time 
came  when  the  environment  changed  and  their  extermina- 
tion proceeded.  If  the  fit  were  plucked  by  accident,  and  it 
was  exceptional,  yet  the  weeding  still  went  on  until  ones  of 
just  as  high  a  level  of  fitness  were  produced.  Nature 
works  slowly  now  through  painful  education  (each  age 
building  upon  the  knowledge  gained  by  the  preceding  ages 
from  their  diligence  and  to  a  less  extent  their  lack  of  it 
and  mistakes)  and  reaching  a  higher  social  scale,  after 
having  gone  as  far  as  possible  with  painful  extermination, 
(natural  selection  has  caused  reason  which  has  supplanted 
instinct  and  selection  as  factors  in  our  development)  toward 
that  consummation,  the  craving  for  which  has  produced 
the  greatest  hope  of  the  human  breast — knowledge  and 
happiness  (perfect  adaptation  to  environment).  Thus 
science  confirms  with  positive  knowledge  that  these  beliefs 
which  originated  in  the  heart  of  primitive  man,  are  not 
empty  and  groundless,  but  even  confirms  them  along  with 
that  other — of  an  omnipresent,  omnipotent  God,  which  it 


AUTOMATISM.  Ill 

explains  as  a  realization  of  the  presence  of  The  Law  (of 
cause-effect). 

The  morphine  fiend  could  not  help  himself  because  he 
was  fated  from  eternity  to  pain;  he  had  better  not  been 
born ;  but  the  law  of  life  and  of  death  cares  not  if  a  spark 
of  consciousness  suffer  nor  whether  the  spark  know  the 
consequences  of  its  action  or  not.  "Ignorance  of  the  law 
is  no  excuse,  and  the  wages  of  sin  is  death."  Whether  the 
victim  is  able  to  help  his  action  or  not  the  evil  to  him 
exists  and  although  the  act  is  an  "evil"  which,  according 
to  free-will,  might  not  have  been,  it  happened  and  the 
universe,  be  it  a  monism  or  dualism,  possess  we  one  element 
(causality)  or  two  elements  (causality  and  free-will),  is 
responsible  for  its  existence  and  the  victim  a  right  to 
pessimism  as  long  as  he  regards  himself.  In  either  doc- 
trine the  only  way  out  of  the  difficulty  that  I  can  see  is  to 
take  the  more  comprehensive  view,  whether  you  be  the 
victim  or  not.  The  invisibility  and  slow  working  of  the 
evolutionary  law  (physical,  mental,  or  social)  may  make 
this  seem  to  be  closet  philosophy,  but  it  is  only  when  we 
make  a  retrospection  of  the  ages  that  the  great  underlying 
influences  come  into  broad  daylight. 

Let  us  take,  by  way  of  illustration,  an  event  told  by  Dr. 
James.  He  says:  "At  Brockton,  the  other  day,  a  man, 
to  get  rid  of  the  wife  whose  existence  bored  him,  inveigled 
her  into  a  desert  spot,  shot  her  four  times  and  then  as  she 
lay  on  the  ground  and  said  to  him,  'You  didn't  do  it  on 
purpose,  did  you  dear  ?'  replied,  'No,  I  didn't  do  it  on  pur- 
pose/ as  he  raised  a  rock  and  smashed  her  skull."  The 
Doctor  remarks,  "We  feel  that  although  a  perfect  mechan- 
ical fit  to  the  rest  of  the  universe,  it  is  a  bad  moral  fit  and 
that  something  else  would  really  have  been  better  in  its 
place."  I  do  not  say  that  something  else  would  not  have 
been  better  in  its  place,  but  his  universe,  as  well  as  mine, 
must  account  for  it  and  palliate  the  crime  to  us  with  a 


112  THE  MONIST. 

reason  which  gains  our  moral  approbation  for  its  existence. 
I  say  that  our  moral  view  is  not  the  true  view,  else  it  would 
allow  the  existence  of  these  "evils/'  No  evil  is  necessary, 
but  as  long  as  we  are  ignorant  or  governed  by  blind  pas- 
sion, we  are  not  perfect  in  our  environment,  and  the  "evils" 
are  bound  to  exist.  The  causes  of  such  actions  as  these 
are  unhealthy  bodies,  or  minds  which  have  not  learned 
from  their  own  or  others  experience  (i.  e.,  educated  to 
a  wrong  environment),  or  who  do  not  recognize  the 
stronger  demands  of  society  or  are  guided  by  passion  in 
lieu  of  the  only  legitimate  monitor  reason.  Now,  seeing 
these  causes,  could  we  blame  the  action  of  this  Brockton 
man  ?  Or  could  we  blame  the  universe  as  immoral  when  it 
is  necessary  to  evolve  slowly  into  the  social  state  and 
therefore  actions  such  as  this,  reversions,  come  to  pass  in 
a  state  of  society  where  they  are  immoral — individual 
strife  was  not  immoral  where  individualism  and  natural 
selection  were  working  as  it  led  to  a  great  good, — the 
physical  and  brain  development  of  the  race.  But  reason, 
experience,  and  social  or  moral  education  are  taking  place 
and  the  future  we  believe  to  promise  a  better  condition. 
There  is  no  more  immorality  in  this  mental  reversion  than 
in  a  physical  reversion  such  as  the  famous  Miss  Julia  Pas- 
trana or  a  tailed  boy.  In  fact,  unless  the  experience  of 
the  past  and  our  possession  of  reason  counted  for  some- 
thing in  our  life,  I  do  not  see  how  any  social  evolution, 
an  optimistic  view  of  the  future,  or  any  reason  for  our 
progress  thus  far  can  be  had,  since  natural  selection  has 
become  nil  to  us.  The  conscious  experience  of  healthy  men 
affirms  the  potency  of  reason  and  experience  and  as  this 
is  the  surest  of  reality  to  us,  I  believe  no  doubt  can  be  had. 
Even  if  there  were  no  other  palliation  to  our  just  desire 
for  a  rational  and  moral  universe,  the  fact  of  the  educa- 
tional value  of  this  Brockton  example  as  an  admonition  to 
posterity  would  be  sufficient. 


AUTOMATISM.  113 

But  this  action  which  I  have  just  explained  is  rudi- 
mentary— the  remains  of  a  lower  stage  of  mental  evolu- 
tion. The  self-instinct  was  necessarily  the  first  produced 
by  natural  selection  and  still  remains  with  us  although  not 
playing  such  an  important  part.  The  preservation  of  the 
young  or  the  family  next  arose  and  all  actions  were  sacri- 
ficed to  it ;  outside  of  the  family  the  self-instinct  was  then 
guide.  So  lived  our  remote  ancestors.  But  the  develop- 
ment of  the  brain  meant  the  birth  of  memory,  comparison, 
and  reason,  for  those  individuals  who  possessed  a  little 
better  memory  of  the  consequences  of  actions  were  able  to 
determine  what  would  be  the  most  probable  result  of  one 
not  yet  performed  and  so  could  better  serve  their  self  or 
family  instincts.  Thus  with  the  birth  of  reason,  instinct 
became  but  a  secondary  factor,  and  our  primitive  ancestors, 
reasoning  that  a  greater  surety  of  food  and  protection  was 
given  by  that  social  institution,  the  tribe,  formed  in  those 
more  efficient  bodies,  which  had  a  greater  scope  of  action 
than  was  possible  for  an  individual.  Natural  selection 
still  kept  up  a  certain  low  standard  within  the  tribe  (by 
rivalry  for  females  and  by  disease)  and  also  outside  of  the 
tribe  by  selecting  those  tribes  of  the  greatest  population 
or  best  organization,  thus  spreading  tribal  formation  over 
the  continents.  But  to-day  with  the  decrease  of  rivalry 
inside  and  outside  of  our  social  institutions,  i.  e.,  decrease 
of  war,  disease  and  personal  conflict,  natural  selection  has 
become  almost  inert.  Our  evolution — the  evolution  of  our 
organization — is  proceeding  by  means  of  the  reasoning 
powers  of  man  and  by  the  necessity  for  social  action  forced 
upon  him  by  his  fellows.  In  early  life  he  imitates  and  then 
sees  the  reason  and  expediency  of  social  action.  The  self- 
instinct,  the  love  instinct,  the  family  instinct  are  here  to 
stay,  but  as  social  evolution  advances  all  actions  are  not 
caused  by  the  first  or  as  later  by  the  first  and  second  or  as 
later  when  the  field  of  action  was  divided  among  the  first, 


114  THE  MONIST. 

second  and  third,  but  the  field  of  each  of  these  instincts 
approaches  its  limits  as  the  broader  fields  of  service  to  the 
nation,  and  later  to  society,  develop. 

Thus  we  see  that  natural  selection  produced  a  high 
type  of  individual,  produced  the  self-instinct,  the  family- 
instinct,  and  had  a  small  part  in  producing  the  tribe  semi- 
instinct.  Then  as  reason  also  developed  and  partly  by  it, 
by  instinct,  or  by  imitation,  men  banded  into  nations,  nat- 
ural selection  slowly  subsided  and  organization  and  edu- 
cation appeared.  The  self-instinct  of  the  leaders  was  lim- 
ited by  the  strength  of  the  demands  of  the  others  even  as 
it  is  to-day,  the  difference  being  in  the  strength  of  the 
demands.  People  seldom  obtain  any  more  than  they  de- 
mand as  self-instinct  has  the  field  (produces  actions)  until 
it  is  encroached  upon  by  the  stronger  demands  of  our  fel- 
lows. Thus  the  only  moral  law,  and  the  only  expedient 
mode  of  action  for  ourselves  is  to  comply  with  the  stronger 
social  demands  as  far  as  they  extend — not  so  far  that  we 
are  overcome  by  the  self-action  of  others.  Thus  we  must 
fight  individually  to  the  extent  that  individualism  is  prac- 
ticed by  others  and  must  conform  to  the  growing  demand 
for  social  action — but  not  as  far  as  the  new  twigs  which 
must  find  nourishment  and  grow  before  they  will  bear  our 
weight.  The  cause  of  great  suffering  has  been  and  will 
be,  (until  the  limit — utilitarianism — is  reached  through 
education)  in  social  evolution,  in  determining  how  far,  in 
regard  to  one's  self,  social  action  encroaches  our  field  of 
expedient  self-action.  In  the  most  successful  lives  this  di- 
viding line  is  more  approximately  determined,  and  those 
are  unfortunates,  who  from  lack  of  observation  or  fore- 
sight act  either  as  the  criminal,  robber,  small  tyrant,  etc., 
(too  much  individualism)  or  such  few  and  unnatural  men 
as  Timon  of  Athens  of  whom  it  could  be  said: 

"Poor  honest  lord,  brought  low  by  his  own  heart, 
Undone  by  goodness !   Strange  unusual  blood, 
When  man's  worst  sin  is,  he  does  too  much  good !" 


AUTOMATISM.  IIS 

They  are  to  be  pitied,  but  that  which  caused  their  action 
cannot  be  censured  as  immoral  because  it  is  a  necessary 
accompaniment  of  the  individual-social  metamorphosis,  and 
all  admit  that  the  end  of  social  evolution  is  one  of  the  great- 
est goods  attainable  by  man. 

At  the  present  day  an  excellent  example  of  this  is  af- 
forded by  the  action  of  Germany  in  European  affairs,  and 
is  applicable  individually  as  well  as  nationally.  Germany 
has  asserted  her  self-rights  as  far  as  possible.  She  has 
exacted  Alsace-Lorraine  from  France  and  is  now  endeav- 
oring to  shut  her  out  of  Morocco.  It  is  a  case  of  get  as 
much  as  you  can  without  burning  your  fingers.  Now  were 
England,  France,  and  Russia  to  form  a  coalition,  a  strong 
demand  would  be  created  and,  being  expedient,  Germany 
would  have  to  comply  with  it.  This  is  of  course  explaining 
the  extreme  expedient  selfish  case  as  it  exists  to-day.  But 
there  are  others  against  whom  there  is  not  so  strong  an 
individual  competition  and  who  then  can  comply  also  with 
the  lesser  demands  of  society.  As  social  evolution  pro- 
gresses these  necessarily  become  greater  in  numbers  and 
the  evolution  gains  increasing  force  as  it  advances.  As 
the  child's  first  social  acts  are  imitative  and  educationally 
induced  and  as  later  he  sees  the  expediency  of  social  insti- 
tutions and  demands,  so  progresses  his  moral  education. 
And  if  he  has  the  self-instinct  strongly  developed,  its  field 
of  action  in  him  will  be  limited  only  by  the  strongest  and 
most  immediate  demands  of  society — demands  which  re- 
quire the  minimum  amount  of  social  action  only,  and  he 
will  not  contribute  to  social  progress.  But  those  in  whom 
the  instinct  is  not  of  such  force  or  who  have  been  educated 
in  highly  organized  communities,  do  not  stop  social  action 
and  revert  to  self-action  only  at  the  strongest  demands 
of  society,  but  comply  with  the  lesser  demands ;  themselves 
create  lesser  demands  and  strengthen  the  pre-existing 
ones,  so  that  the  social  evolution  of  any  community  or 


Il6  THE  MONIST. 

people  depends  on  the  number  of  this  type  of  individual 
that  it  contains — if  the  self-actors  predominate  evolution 
would  necessarily  tend  to  revert  to  the  remote  unsocial 
period  and  vice  versa.  The  great  factor  in  producing  the 
less  selfish  actors  in  the  majority  is,  that  once  headed  in 
the  direction  (usually  by  education)  like  habit,  the  tend- 
ency is  to  let  the  field  of  self-instinct  be  encroached  upon 
gradually  more  and  more  (of  course  retaining  as  much 
of  the  instinct  as  is  required  by  expediency  to  combat  with 
the  amount  of  self-action  of  others  at  the  stage  of  evolu- 
tion of  the  time  of  the  individual).  Thus  the  field  of 
social  action  widens  and  limits  that  of  self-action.  New 
demands  are  created,  by  a  majority;  the  former  weak  ones 
strengthened,  and  the  strong  ones  are  become  a  matter  of 
course  and  habit. 

It  is  apparent  from  this  how  any  set  rule  for  moral 
action  has  only  been  valid  for  the  state  of  society  at  its 
birth,  and  how  in  order  to  lead  the  most  satisfactory  life 
we  must  comprehend  (approximately)  the  existing  state 
of  social  evolution — must  observe  and  follow  the  amount 
of  social  action  that  can  be  indulged  in  without  neglecting 
the  individual  action  necessary  to  maintain  one's  self.  Thus 
utilitarianism  in  being  the  consummation  of  moral  or  so- 
cial evolution — all  actions  for  the  good  of  society  and  the 
maximum  individual  welfare  possible  for  all  (the  welfare 
of  society's  individuals  being  its  own)  is  not  a  fit  "working 
hypothesis"  to-day  as  a  certain  amount  of  self-action  must 
be  mixed  with  the  social.  It  is,  I  believe,  the  goal  of  social 
evolution — distant,  undiscernible,  on  the  other  brow  of  the 
earth — and  we  know  the  earth  is  round.  Utilitarianism, 
service  substituted  for  gain,  thus  seems  the  far  off  end 
of  moral  action. 

I  can  in  no  way  agree  with  M.  Elie  Metchnikoff,  who, 
after  showing  the  insufficiencies  of  the  moral  doctrines 
of  Kant  and  Spencer  says,  'The  ideal  will  rather  be  that 


AUTOMATISM.  117 

of  men  who  will  be  self-sufficient  and  who  will  no  longer 
permit  others  to  do  them  good"  —  in  other  words  the 
super-man  of  Nietzsche.  He,  a  biologist  and  scientist, 
fails  to  scan  the  field  of  organic  development  and  does 
not  see  that  organization  is  the  keyword  to  all  progress 
in  that  field.  The  organization  of  "chromideals"  into 
cells;  the  organization  of  cells  into  communities  or  organ- 
isms and  lastly  the  organization  of  organisms  into  what 
we  call  nations  and  states.  The  key-word  to  organization 
is  not  self-sufficiency  but  specialization,  cooperation,  recip- 
rocal action.  The  cells  perform  different  functions  and 
loyally  work  with  the  welfare  of  all  the  other  cells  (the 
community)  in  view,  and  the  organism  or  community  can 
function  where  the  single  cell  could  not.  The  analogy  is 
complete.  He  fails  to  see  that  in  order  for  the  family  to 
exist,  one  member  must  procure  food  and  protection,  one 
must  raise  the  offspring,  and  the  offspring  when  indepen- 
dent can  then  become  the  head  of  another  family  (it  being 
necessary  for  the  higher  action  of  the  animal  that  its  in- 
fantile development  be  longer).  In  the  tribe  some  must 
procure  food,  others  make  implements,  others  protect,  etc., 
in  order  that  individually  the  tribe  may  better  live  and 
function  in  accordance  with  a  more  complex  environment. 
Would  this  not  be  a  low  social  state  if  each  individual  had 
to  grow  or  hunt  his  own  food,  manufacture  his  clothes, 
his  house,  his  vehicles,  etc.  ?  He  would  be  self-sufficient 
and  no  one  would  be  doing  him  good ! 

The  relations  of  the  part  to  the  whole  in  any  highly 
specialized  society  are  analogous  to  those  of  the  vital  or- 
gans to  the  human  body.  There  is  paralysis  throughout 
the  system  when  its  functions  are  interrupted.  The  lower 
forms  of  life  are  so  simple  that  you  cut  and  subdivide  them 
at  will  without  any  impairment  of  vitality,  but  as  organi- 
zation develops,  with  a  circulatory  system  and  coordinate 
functions  for  the  several  parts,  their  independence  is  lost. 


Il8  THE  MONIST. 

And  so  in  a  primitive  society  the  individual  is  compara- 
tively independent,  but  as  organization  takes  place  and 
specialization  proceeds  and  the  exchanges  of  civilized  life 
develop,  the  well-being  of  the  individual  becomes  more 
and  more  dependent  upon  his  cooperation  with  the  other 
individuals.  "Our  civilization  is  based  upon  the  division 
of  labor.  Its  industrial  efficiency,  its  wealth  of  production, 
its  comfort  and  luxuries  and  variety  of  opportunity,  are 
the  results  of  cooperative  effort.  If  each  member  of  the 
community,  instead  of  supplying  his  own  wants,  devotes 
himself  to  one  thing  and  all  exchange  the  surplus  products 
with  each  other,  the  sum-total  of  their  production  and  pos- 
sessions is  increased."  Specialization  and  not  self-suffi- 
ciency is  the  first  word  in  organization,  civilization,  and 
social  evolution. 

Society  is  automatically  regulated,  for  each  man  will 
select  as  his  vocation  that  mode  of  action  for  which  society 
pays  most  and  which  he  believes  himself  capable  of  ful- 
filling, i.  e.,  to  him  the  strongest  demanded  (highest  paid) 
mode  of  action.  And  according  to  his  ability  will  he  suc- 
ceed in  supplying  the  demand  or  descending  to  a  position 
where  he  can.  To  trace  the  demands  of  society  upon  the 
individual,  is  to  trace  the  social  and  moral  evolution  of  the 
race. 

I  can  see  nothing  but  benefit  and  increase  of  happiness 
from  the  struggle  of  the  old  with  the  increasing  new  idea 
of  social  duty  and  in  the  unhappiness,  pain,  and  sorrow 
caused  by  the  non-conformity  of  those  unlucky  individuals 
who  lacked  the  wisdom  to  obey  the  demands  of  society  as 
far  as  these  went,  or  who  disregarded  the  necessary,  indi- 
vidual self-action  for  their  happiness  in  that  state  of  social 
evolution.  The  battle  has  brought  and  is  bringing  our 
more  complete  organization  and  individual  specialization, 
and  hence  greater  individual  safety  from  disease,  from  im- 
proper education  and  from  all  such  mistakes  and  imper- 


AUTOMATISM.  IIQ 

factions  as  now  exist  in  our  governmental  and  labor  or- 
ganization. The  mistakes  are  a  benefit  to  posterity  as  it 
learns  from  them  what  should  be  built  upon  the  present 
inherited  foundation  to  further  the  completion  of  the  struc- 
ture. 

So  I  have  shown  the  reasons,  the  why,  the  by-cause  of 
our  social  actions — which  form  a  great  percent  of  all  our 
actions,  and  have  also  shown  therefore  that  they  are  no 
less  automatic  than  the  others.  And  not  only  that  but  I 
have  palliated  to  our  demands  for  a  completely  good,  un- 
sullied universe,  the  number  of  so-called  evils, — the  sor- 
rows and  pains,  which  have  arisen  along  with  the  social 
evolution  as  well  as  those  which  have  arisen  from  the 
physical  evolution. 

It  is  asked,  what  is  the  meaning,  the  import,  the  pur- 
pose of  it  all,  why  the  necessity  of  this  development  ?  I  can 
only  answer,  the  universe  is  infinite.  What  could  be  the 
purpose  of  the  purpose,  or  the  import  of  the  import  ?  Were 
matter  absolutely  dense — without  motion,  we  would  have 
no  problem;  but  change  is  the  second  most  apparent  phe- 
nomenon. There  can  be  but  one  kind  of  change  and  that 
is  of  the  position  of  matter.  This  may  be  resolved  into 
molecular  and  molar  motion.  If  a  change  in  the  kind  of 
motion  is  made  it  is  in  the  cycle  of  molecular  to  molar  and 
by  contact  of  bodies  back  into  molecular  motion.  There 
is  no  purpose,  that  is  too  human  a  mode  of  thinking.  There 
is  but  one  possible  process  and  that  is  change.  In  the 
universe  existence  and  necessity  are  the  factors;  they  are 
not  finite  as  the  mind,  but  free — on  account  of  themselves 
alone.  I  sit  and  watch  the  development  of  a  crystal — of 
which  we  are  the  molecules,  our  cells  atoms,  and  our 
"chromidials"  ions.  The  change  of  this  crystal  is  molec- 
ular into  the  more  substantial  molar  state  accompanying 
and  a  part  of  the  earth's  change  from  nebulous  to  a  more 
solid  condition.  There  is  as  much  import  in  our  develop- 


I2O  THE  MONIST. 

ment  as  the  development  of  a  grain  of  salt  from  solution, 
and  the  performance  of  the  experiment  is  a  show  con- 
tinuous. So  much  for  the  metaphysics  of  the  question. 

I  have  now,  I  believe,  covered  the  entire  scope  of  phe- 
nomena, have  shown  the  reasons, — the  causes  of  all  actions, 
individual  and  social,  and  have  shown  how  each  leads  life 
on  to  "a  consummation  devoutly  to  be  wished."  Thus  the 
dread  figure  of  "evil"  has  been  exposed  as  a  negative  quan- 
tity while  we  admit  and  try  to  exterminate  the  to  us  evil. 
I  have  shown  that  we  can  blame  nothing  and  that  an  op- 
timism concerning  the  universe  and  its  automatism  is  enter- 
tainable.  Viscount  Amberly  has  written,  "Not  in  so  slov- 
enly a  manner  has  the  work  of  nature  been  performed. 
We  are  no  more  free  to  disturb  the  harmony  and  beauty 
of  the  universe  than  are  the  stars  in  their  courses  or  the 
planets  in  their  orbits  .  Our  courses  and  orbits  are  no  less 
fixed  than  theirs,  and  it  is  but  the  imperfection  of  our 
knowledge,  if  they  have  not  been  and  cannot  yet  be  dis- 
covered. But  it  would  be  a  lamentable  blot  upon  a  uni- 
verse, where  all  things  are  fixed  by  a  law  'in  whom  there 
is  no  variableness  nor  shadow  of  turning'  were  there  per- 
mitted to  exist  a  race  of  creatures  who  were  a  law  unto 
themselves."  It  is  already  recognized  that  knowledge  re- 
pays a  hundredfold  the  sweat  that  it  cost  us  in  this  martyr- 
dom of  man,  for  we  are  thereby  enabled  to  govern  our 
future  actions  with  greater  wisdom  and  with  more  perfect 
reasoning,  so  I  need  not  lay  so  great  stress  upon  the  almost 
omnipotence  of  the  environment,  the  education  of  us  all. 

Thus,  in  the  belief  that  "Alles  verstehen  ist  Alles  dul- 
den"  I  widen  my  moral  horizon  from  that  of  Dr.  James, 
and  find  no  phenomenon  caused  by  that  law-perfect-in- 
itself :  cause-effect,  which  is  not  perfect  mechanically  and 
morally.  I  make  suffering  a  good  and  destroy  the  word 
evil.  Concerning  the  necessity  for  "evil";  there  is  no  ne- 
cessity and  its  existence  is  only  caused  by  our  imperfec- 


AUTOMATISM.  121 

tion,  our  ignorance.  I  no  more  regret  the  above  incidents 
than  I  commend  one  of  the  opposite  character  (except  for 
purpose  of  encouragement)  or  blame  hydrochloric  acid  for 
acting  upon  zinc.  If  they  say,  well  then  there  is  no  use 
in  our  trying,  things  will  happen  as  set  from  eternity,  I  say, 
unless  you  do  act  according  to  that  necessary  instinct  and 
competent  memory  you  will  justly  become  a  victim  and 
you  or  your  life,  if  nothing  of  an  opposite  influence  affect 
you  or  it,  will  justly  become  martyrs  and  perish  in  the 
cause  of  good.  Nature  cares  nothing  for  individuals  and 
it  is  the  individual's  self-instinct  which  has  brought  the 
free-will  and  immortality  doctrines  into  being.  "The  op- 
timism of  scientific  minds  rests  in  the  belief  that  upon  the 
physical  plane — the  development  of  bodily  vigor,  or  upon 
the  intellectual  plane — making  him  capable  of  reasoning 
and  thinking  for  himself,  or  upon  the  ethical  plane — mak- 
ing him  a  useful,  trustworthy  human  being,  all  dependent 
upon  beneficial  heredity  and  educational  environment,  that 
mankind  must  be  strong,  able  and  free,  and  that  we  shall 
not  dwindle  into  physical  weaklings,  intellectual  nonenti- 
ties, or  spiritual  slaves  or  fanatics."  Munro  continues, 
"Life  consists  in  the  free  exercise  of  our  faculties  and 
happiness  in  the  successful  performance  of  duty  and 
achievement."  Indeed  I  am  sure  we  can  rely  upon  that 
factor  which  exterminates  human  inertness,  and  without 
which  I  can  see  no  advancement,  no  cause  for  the  struggle 
and  no  justification  of  evil  to  our  moral  natures. 

Some  say  that  the  effect  of  this  belief  on  them  would 
be  a  feeling  of  a  weight  and  pressure  of  the  rule  of  mech- 
anism, that  they  must  feel  free  in  order  to  remain  happy 
and  that  there  is  something  uncanny  in  regarding  living 
creatures  as  mere  complicated  machines.  These  are  cer- 
tain preconceived  ideas,  arising,  not  from  a  change  of  belief 
induced  by  reason  or  by  considering,  as  I  have  shown,  that 
the  will  to  us  exists,  but  from  a  certain  fear  of  the  un- 


122  THE  MONIST. 

accustomed  caused  by  the  absence  or  removal  of  a  belief 
which  had  become  a  habit.  Many  peoples  have  lived  happy 
with  no  feeling  of  oppression  and  been  fatalists, — such  as 
the  old  Anglo-Saxons  and  their  wierd  or  fate,  the  Arabians 
and  Persians  who  saw  in  all  that  took  place  the  inevitable 
will  of  Allah,  or,  in  more  recent  times,  the  Calvinists  and 
others  who  betook  themselves  to  this  belief  as  the  great  and 
only  consolation  against  the  wrongs  and  injustices  of  the 
world.  They  were  taught  the  belief ;  it  was  a  part  of  them 
the  same  as  the  idea  of  free  willing  is  a  part  of  the  majority 
of  people  to-day  and  so  the  opposite  doctrine  repulsive.  We 
are  thus  human.  It  is  a  simple  matter  of  attaining  the  cor- 
rect attitude  of  mind  and  accustoming  oneself  to  the  idea, 
which  is  facilitated  by  the  fact  that  will  to  us  exists  and  that 
mechanism  is  more  rational,  more  truthful,  and  more  easily 
conceived. 

A  few  more  remarks  will  conclude  all  that  I  have  to  say. 
The  belief  that  events  are  determinedly  related  to  the  con- 
dition of  things  immediately  preceding  them,  is  now  held 
by  all  important  thinkers  in  respect  to  all  kinds  of  phe- 
nomena except  higher  animal  volitions.  In  each  successive 
department  of  fact,  conflicting  modes  of  thought  have  re- 
ceded and  faded  until  at  last  they  have  vanished  every- 
where except  from  this  "mysterious  citadel  of  the  will." 
Then  if  we  have  any  regard  for  consistency,  and  any  re- 
gard for  what  facts,  so  far  as  we  can  see,  tend  to  state,  it 
is  without  the  least  disturbance  of  our  scientific  conscience 
that  we  can  hold,  until  otherwise  proven,  that  man  is  only 
a  more  complicated  and  variously  endowed  automaton, 
physical  causes  solely  determining  his  bodily  actions;  the 
molecular  activities  of  his  cerebrum  producing  the  succes- 
sion of  his  mental  states ;  and  brain  changes  the  real  origin 
of  those  movements  he  is  accustomed  to  regard  as  express- 
ing his  feelings,  or  as  executing  his  intentions,  those  feel- 
ings and  intentions  being  the  mere  "concomitant  symbols 


AUTOMATISM.  123 

in  consciousness."  That  the  universe  ought  to  be  rational 
is  what  these  conscious  feelings  tell  us,  and  I  think  I  have 
ascertained  that  most  rational  conception,  monism.  Reason 
should  be  satisfied  and  I  have  shown  that  all  things  are  gov- 
erned according  to  that  reason  which  actuates  them.  Know- 
ing that  we  cannot  help  doing  what  our  heredity  and  en- 
vironment necessitates,  I  have  inferred  the  direction  that 
may  be  given  to  the  whole  course  of  a  life  by  a  little  effort 
on  the  part  of  another  to  fit  the  man  better  to  his  surround- 
ings and  to  insure  his  well-being.  And  lastly,  the  most 
important,  I  have  shown  that  we  may  entertain  an  opti- 
mism concerning  the  universe,  a  view  at  once  so  necessary 
to  our  peace  of  mind  and  to  our  obtaining  the  best  out  of  an 
existence  where  life  must  be  thought  worth  the  living  and 
the  struggle  to  repay  its  cost.  In  fact  I  see  no  reason  why 
we  should  not  welcome  with  open  arms  a  conception  so 
beneficial  to  the  body,  to  the  understanding  and  to  the 
craving  of  the  heart. 

STEWART  P.  FOLTZ. 
ASHEVILLE,  N.  C. 


GELLERT'S  PHILOSOPHICAL  POETRY. 

ADOPTED  BY  BEETHOVEN  AS  THE  CONFESSION  OF  HIS  RE- 
LIGIOUS FAITH. 

BEETHOVEN  was  born  a  Roman  Catholic  and  in  his 
early  childhood  he  received  impressions  exclusively 
of  Catholic  traditions,  Catholic  worship,  and  Catholic  art. 
It  must  always  have  appeared  to  the  boy  that  the  Catholic 
church  was  the  only  religious  institution.  When  he  left  the 
city  of  his  childhood  and  youth  whose  government  was  in  the 
hands  of  a  prince-archbishop,  one  of  the  electors  of  the  Holy 
Roman  empire,  he  came  to  Vienna  which  is  now  and  was 
especially  in  his  days  a  typically  Roman  Catholic  city.  It 
is  remarkable  that  under  these  circumstances  he  was  not 
more  limited  in  his  religious  conviction  and  art  by  the 
ecclesiastical  influence  which  had  a  strong  hold,  for  in- 
stance, on  Liszt.  Beethoven's  religion  had  broadened 
under  the  influence  of  his  acquaintance  with  other  world- 
conceptions,  and  it  appears  that  Gellert  contributed  most 
to  the  formation  of  his  views. 

Beethoven  was  a  great  reader,  and  we  can  trace  the 
growth  of  his  conceptions  not  only  by  the  books  he  read  but 
also  by  the  very  sentences  which  impressed  him,  for  he 
had  a  habit  of  underlining  what  struck  him  forcibly,  and 
thus  we  can  trace  his  philosophical  and  religious  develop- 
ment. Though  he  never  broke  away  from  the  church,  he 
broadened,  and  his  general  attitude  was  not  greatly  dif- 
ferent from  that  of  any  other  great  man  of  his  age.  He 


GELLERT'S  PHILOSOPHICAL  POETRY.  125 

admired  Goethe  though  the  two  men  were  too  different  in 
character  and  disposition  to  become  friends. 

Beethoven's  religion  was  strongly  tinted  by  the  ra- 
tionalism of  the  Kantian  school.  His  God  was  not  the 
miracle  worker,  not  the  God  who  had  revealed  himself 
exclusively  to  Jews  and  Christians,  and  yet  Beethoven  did 
not  hesitate  to  lend  his  art  to  the  composition  of  a  great 
mass.  He  was  too  broad  to  reject  the  artistic  conception 
of  a  religion  the  dogmas  of  which  he  had  outgrown. 

As  a  rule  when  people  broaden  they  become  narrow  in 
the  very  field  of  their  mental  growth.  They  love  to  parade 
their  breadth  of  mind  by  objecting  to  those  forms  which 
characterize  the  narrower  views.  Not  so  Beethoven.  He 
did  not  frequent  the  church  or  attend  service,  but  he  did 
not  hesitate,  when  the  opportunity  offered,  to  write  a 
mass  for  his  friend  the  archduke  Rudolf  at  his  installation 
as  archbishop  of  Olmutz,  utilizing  the  traditional  form 
of  service  that  was  customary  in  the  Roman  Catholic 
church.  But  his  composition  outgrew  the  limits  of  its 
earlier  form.  It  became  a  cosmic  epic,  a  doxology  of  the 
Creator,  a  triumphal  song  of  God's  glory  and  a  proclama- 
tion of  his  divine  dispensation. 

The  composition  of  this  Missa  Solemnis  is  no  longer 
ecclesiastical  in  style.  It  has  become  poetry,  and  as  such 
the  Roman  Catholic  mode  of  worship  serves  as  the  basis 
for  the  presentation  of  a  broader  theme.  It  is  like  a 
philosophical  drama  in  music;  it  is  the  denouement  of 
the  entire  world  process,  an  anthem  to  the  infinitude  of 
existence  and  the  victorious  advance  of  evolution,  a  hymn 
to  the  world-order. 

In  this  same  sense  we  have  to  interpret  also  Bee- 
thoven's compositions  of  the  six  religious  songs  of  Gel- 
lert.  They  are  Protestant  in  tone  and  Protestant  in  the 
austerity  of  their  devotion.  Beethoven  accepts  them  not 
in  the  letter  of  the  word  but  more  as  an  artistic  attitude 


126  THE  MONIST. 

to  express  his  own  sentiments.  We  cannot  doubt  that 
upon  the  whole  he  made  the  thoughts  his  own,  and 
here  in  Gellert's  songs,  if  anywhere,  is  expressed  his 
own  religious  conviction.  From  the  sentiment  of  the  sixth 
of  these  songs,  called  "Penitential  Hymn,"  the  present 
generation  has  become  estranged,  and  it  will  be  difficult 
for  us  to  understand  Beethoven's  attitude ;  but  it  will  ex- 
plain itself  if  we  consider  that  Beethoven  in  his  constant 
fear  of  appearing  insincere  frequently  gave  offense  to  his 
best  friends,  and  then  showed  his  regret  by  profuse  ac- 
knowledgement of  his  mistake.  These  outbursts  of  temper 
and  an  ostensible  show  of  discourtesy  toward  his  very  best 
friends,  most  of  whom  belonged  to  the  highest  circles  of  the 
Austrian  aristocracy,  are  mainly  due  to  his  democratic 
pride  and  to  the  fear  lest  he  depart  from  his  ideal  of  inde- 
pendence. It  was  for  the  sake  of  the  God  within  him  that 
he  was  carried  away  to  brusqueness  and  rude  behavior,  and 
he  felt  the  adjustment  had  to  be  made  with  himself  before 
God  alone. 

We  here  insert  a  translation  of  the  six  hymns  of  Gel- 
lert,  following  mainly  the  translation  of  H.  Stevens.  They 
read  as  follows : 

PRAYER. 

O  Lord,  thy  goodness  reaches  far, 

As  far  the  clouds  are  guided ; 

By  mercy  crown'd,  thy  creatures  are 

With  needful  help  provided. 

Lord!  my  defense,  my  tower  and  shield, 

To  me  a  gracious  audience  yield, 

Approve  my  supplication. 

LOVE  THY  NEIGHBOR. 

If  one  shall  say,  "I  love  the  Lord," 
While  yet  his  brother  hating, 


GELLERT'S  PHILOSOPHICAL  POETRY.  127 

With  mockers  he  shall  reap  reward, 
God's  truth  abominating; 
For  God  is  love,  and  wishes  me 
With  all  on  loving  terms  to  be. 

DEATH. 

Life  is  ebbing  fast  away, 
Hourly  towards  the  grave  I  hasten ; 
Death  may  come  without  delay, 
Let  this  thought  my  spirit  chasten. 
Man  bethink  thee  Death  is  rife, 
One  thing  needful  is  in  life. 

NATURE  PRAISES  GOD. 

The  Heavens  declare  the  Lord's  infinite  glory, 

The  sea  and  earth  sound  forth  his  name, 

And  tell  their  origin's  wonderful  story, 

Mark  well,  O  Man,  what  they  proclaim. 

Who  gave  the  numberless  stars  their  existence, 

Who  calls  the  Sun  from  his  abode, 

He  cames  in  brightness  and  smiles  from  the  distance, 

And  like  a  hero  keeps  his  road. 

POWER  OF  GOD. 

God  is  my  song! 

In  strength  he  reigns  victorious, 

High  is  his  name, 

And  all  his  works  are  glorious; 

Earth,  Sea  and  Heaven  to  him  belong. 

PENITENTIAL  HYMN, 
i. 

'Gainst  thee  alone,  God,  have  I  sin  committed, 
And  evil  done  in  thy  dread  sight, 
Thou  seest  my  guilt  for  which  thy  wrath  is  fitted, 
See,  Lord,  my  woe  and  sore  affright. 


128  THE  MONIST. 

My  piteous  wail,  my  sighs  are  all  before  thee, 
My  tears  of  deep  and  bitter  grief. 

0  God,  my  God,  shall  I  in  vain  implore  Thee  ? 
How  long  wilt  thou  deny  relief? 

Lord,  do  not  after  my  deserts  reward  me. 
Chastise  me  not!    Show  me  thy  face; 

1  crave  for  thee !  thy  pardon,  Lord,  accord  me, 
O  God  of  patience  and  of  grace. 


ii. 


0  grant  me  early,  God,  thy  consolation, 
Oh  Father  of  mercy,  God  of  love, 

For  thine  own  name's  sake  grant  my  supplication, 
Thou  lov'st  to  bless  from  Heav'n  above. 

Let  me  thy  pathway  tread;  let  me  be  steady 

In  my  obedience  to  thy  word. 

To  do  thy  will  I  shall  be  always  ready, 

1  am  thy  servant,  thou  my  Lord. 

Lord,  hasten  thou  to  shelter  and  defend  me ; 

Thy  light  shall  lead,  point  out  the  goal. 

Thy  helping  hand,  O  Lord,  thy  helping  hand  extend  me 

And  with  thy  comfort  fill  my  soul. 

PAUL  CARUS. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 
BUDDHIST  LOANS  TO  CHRISTIANITY. 

WITH   SPECIAL  REFERENCE  TO  RICHARD  GARBE. 

In  the  October  Monist  Professor  Garbe,  of  Tubingen,  admits 
a  Buddhist  basis  for  the  Christian  legends  of  Saints  Christopher 
and  Eustace.  In  the  early  part  of  the  same  article  he  also  admits 
Buddhist  influence  in  the  Christian  Apocryphal  Gospels,  but  denies 
it  in  the  Canonical  ones.  I  herewith  submit  two  passages  from  the 
Gospel  of  Luke  which  appear  to  me  to  agree  as  closely  with  the 
earliest  Buddhist  texts  as  do  the  saint-legends  admitted  by  Garbe. 

The  first  parallel  is  taken  from  my  now  forgotten  pamphlet  of 
1905,  Can  the  Pali  Pitakas  aid  us  in  fixing  the  Text  of  the  Gospels? 
The  second  is  from  my  Buddhist  and  Christian  Gospels,  as  indicated 
in  the  first  edition  (1902)  and  partially  printed  in  the  third  and 
fourth  (Tokyo,  1905,  and  Philadelphia,  1908). 

THE   ANGELIC    HERALDS   AND  THEIR   HYMN. 

Sutta    Nipato,    Mahavaggo,    Nalaka- 

Luke  ii.  8-14.  sutta  (known  only  in  Pali,  but  with 

analogues  in  later  Buddhist  books). 

And  there  were  shepherds  in  the  The    heavenly    hosts    rejoicing,    de- 
same  country  abiding  in  the  field,  and  lighted, 

keeping  watch  by  night  over  their  And   Sakko   the   leader   and   angels 

flock.     And   an   angel   of   the   Lord  white-stoled 

stood  by  them,  and  the  glory  of  the  Seizing  their  robes,  and  praising  ex- 
Lord  shone  round  about  them:  and  ceedingly, 

they  were  sore  afraid.  And  the  angel  Did  Asito  the  hermit  see  in  noonday 

said  unto  them,  Be  not  afraid ;  for  be-  .  rest, 
hold,  I  bring  you  good  tidings  of  great 

joy  which  shall  be  to  all  the  people :  for  [He  asks  the  angels  why  they  re- 

thereis   born  to  you  this  day  in  the  city  joice,  and  they  answer:] 
of  David  a  Saviour,  which  is  Christ  the 

Lord.    And  this  is  the  sign  unto  you ;  The  Buddha-to-be,  the  best  and 

Ye    shall    find   a   babe    wrapped    in  matchless  Jewel, 


I3O  THE  MONIST. 

swaddling   clothes,    and   lying   in   a  Is  born  for  weal  and  welfare  in  the 

manger.     And   suddenly   there   was  world  of  men, 

with  the   angel  a  multitude  of  the  In  the  town  of  the  Sakyas,  in  the  re- 

heavenly  host  praising  God,  and  say-  gion  of  Lumbini  i1 

ing,  Therefore  are  we  joyful  and  exceed- 

Glory  to  God  in  the  highest,  ing  glad. 

And  on  earth  peace,  divine  favor 
among  men. 

The  parallel  is  further  carried  out  in  the  narrative.  The  her- 
mit, like  the  shepherds,  goes  to  pay  his  reverence  to  the  newborn 
Saviour. 

Considering  that  between  the  Greek  of  Luke  and  the  Pali  of 
the  Sutta  Nipato  there  may  lie  some  lost  book,  the  words  in  italics 
are  practically  identical.  The  Pali  words  hita-sukhataya  ("for  bles- 
sing and  happiness")  are  a  convenient  phrase,  often  recurring  in 
the  texts.  We  here  translate  them  "weal  and  welfare"  for  the  sake 
of  poetic  effect,  but  they  mean  much  the  same  as  the  English  phrase, 
"peace  and  prosperity."  Now  if  Luke,  or  rather  his  Oriental  inter- 
mediary, did  actually  use  the  Pali  poem,  it  is  evident  that  omitting 
jato  ("born"),  we  find  a  very  good  equivalent  of  the  line: 

Manussaloke  hitasukhatdya  jato, 
in  the  line: 

«ri  TT/S  yys  cipYjvr)  iv  dv0pa>7rois  euSo/aa. 

It  is  thrown  into  the  form  of  a  Hebrew  parallelism,  in  which 
peace  on  earth  and  divine  favor  among  men  are  interchangeable 
terms.  It  is  well  known  that  the  oldest  manuscripts  of  the  New 
Testament  are  at  variance  here  over  the  word  evSo/cia.  Some  read 
cvSoKias  (genitive)  and  then  we  must  render:  "among  men  of  good 
will"  (or  the  divine  favor,  i.  e.,  the  elect,  as  Alford  says). 

This  is  the  reading  of  the  Vulgate  and  of  the  English  and 
American  Revised  Versions.  It  is  because  evSoKia  in  the  Septuagint 
means  so  often  the  divine  good  pleasure  that  the  Revised  Version 
has  "men  in  whom  he  is  well  pleased."  But  the  old  King  James 
reading  (following  the  textus  receptus  afterwards  fixed  by  the 
Dutch  printers  Elzevir)  is  borne  out  by  the  analogy  of  all  Hebrew 
parallelisms.  This  is  therefore  a  passage  wherein  the  Pali  Pitakas 
can  probably  aid  us  in  fixing  the  text  of  the  New  Testament. 

This  parallel  is  ignored  by  Garbe,  though  he  mentions  that  of 
Asito  and  Simeon,  which  is  connected  with  it  in  the  Pali.  But  the 

*A  pre-Christian  inscription  was  lately  discovered,  marking  the  site  of 
Lumbini. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

Lalita  Vistara  and  other  late  books  relied  on  by  Garbe,  and  by  San- 
skrit scholars  generally,  do  not  contain  the  Angelic  Hymn.  I  admit 
the  weakness  of  the  Asito-Simeon  parallel,  when  taken  by  itself; 
but  its  strength  consists  in  its  organic  connection  with  the  Angelic 
Hymn,  both  in  Luke  and  the  Sutta  Nipato. 

In  Buddhist  and  Christian  Gospels  (4th  ed.  only)  I  have  shown 
that  Luke's  alteration  of  the  Buddhist  legends  is  no  more  than  his 
alteration  of  the  Synoptic  tradition  (Mark  xvi.  7,  compared  with 
Luke  xxiv.  6). 

When  all  this  has  been  studied  as  carefully  as  older  points  of 
Gospel  criticism,  the  day  will  come  when  school-children  will  know 
that  "Peace  on  earth,  good  will  to  men"  is  a  Buddhist  text. 

THE   LORD'S   THREE   TEMPTATIONS. 

Classified  Collection,  Book  of  Temp- 
tations   (Pali  and  Chinese). 

In  the  Wilderness. 

And  Jesus,  full  of  the  Holy  Spirit,  At  one  season  the  Lord  was  stay- 
returned  from  the  Jordan,  and  was  ing  in  the  land  of  the  Kosala,  among 
led  by  the  Spirit  in  the  wilderness  the  Himalayas,  in  a  log-hut.  While 
during  forty  days,  being  tempted  of  thus  living  in  hermitage  retired,  the 
the  devil.  And  he  did  eat  nothing  reflection  arose  within  him:  "It  is 
in  those  days;  and  when  they  were  really  possible  to  exercise  dominion 
completed,  he  hungered.  by  righteousness,  without  slaying,  or 

causing  slaughter ;  without  oppression 
or  the  making  thereof;  without  sor- 
row or  the  infliction  thereof." 

Temptations  to  Assume  Empire  and  Transmute  Matter. 
(In  different  order  in  Luke  and  the  Pali.) 

And  the   devil  said  unto  him,   If  Then  Maro,  the  Evil  One,  perceived 

thou  art  the  Son  of  God,  command  in  his  heart  the  thought  which  had 

this  stone  that  it  become  bread.    And  arisen  in  the  heart  of  the  Lord  and 

Jesus  answered  unto  him,  It  is  writ-  he  approached  the  Lord  and  spake 

ten,  Man  shall  not  live  by  bread  alone.  thus :  "Lord,  may  the  Lord  exercise 

And  he  led  him  up?  and  shewed  him  dominion;  may  the  Auspicious  One 

all  the  kingdoms  of  the  world  in  a  exercise   dominion  by  righteousness, 

moment  of  time.    And  the  devil  said  without  slaying  or  causing  slaughter; 

unto  him,  To  thee  will  I  give  all  this  without    oppression    or    the    making 

authority,  and  the  glory  of  them :  for  thereof ;   without  sorrow  or  the  in- 

it  hath  been  delivered  unto  me;  and  fliction  thereof." 

to  whomsoever  I  will  I  give  it.     If  "What   seest  thou  in  me,  O   Evil 

thou   therefore   wilt   worship   before  One,  that  thou  speakest  thus  to  me?" 

a  Matthew  has :  unto  an  exceeding  high  mountain  (thus  agreeing  with  the 
Pali  idea  of  the  Himalayas). 


132 


THE  MONIST. 


me,  it  shall  all  be  thine.  And  Jesus 
answered  and  said  unto  him,  It  is  writ- 
ten, Thou  shalt  worship  the  Lord  thy 
God,  and  him  only  shalt  thou  serve. 


(Continuous  in  Luke). 


"Lord,  the  Lord  hath  practised  the 
four  principles  of  psychical  power, 
hath  developed  them,  made  them  ac- 
tive and  practical,  pursued  them,  ac- 
cumulated, and  striven  to  the  height 
thereof.  So,  Lord,  if  the  Lord  de- 
sired, he  could  turn  the  Himalaya, 
the  monarch  of  mountains,  into  very 
gold,  and  gold  would  the  mountain 
be." 

[Buddha  replies:] 
"The  whole  of  a  mountain  of  gold,  of 

fine  gold, 

Twofold,  were  not  enough  for  one; 
Let  him  who  knoweth  this  govern  his 

life. 
He  who  hath  seen  Pain  and  whence 

its  rise, 

How  could  such  a  one  bow  to  lusts? 
He  who  knoweth  that  the  substratum 

of  existence  is  what  is  called  in  the 

world  'Attachment/ 
Let   that   man  train   himself  in  the 

subdual  thereof." 

Then  Maro,  The  Evil  One,  said, 
"The  Lord  knows  me;  the  Auspicious 
One  knows  me"  And  he  vanished 
thence,  unhappy  and  disconsolate. 

Temptation  to  Commit  Suicide. 

Book  of  the  Great  Decease:  Long 
Collection,  Dialogue  16;  Chinese, 
No.  2.  (Three  months  before  Bud- 
dha's death). 


And  he  led  him  to  Jerusalem,  and 
set  him  on  the  pinnacle  of  the  temple, 
and  said  unto  him,  If  thou  art  the 
Son  of  God,  cast  thyself  down  from 
hence:  for  it  is  written, 
He  shall  give  his  angels  charge  con- 
cerning thee,  to  guard  thee: 
and, 
On  their  hands  they  shall  bear  thee 

up, 

Lest  haply  thou  dash  thy  foot  against 
a  stone. 


Now  not  long  after  St.  Anando 
had  gone,  Maro,  the  Evil  One,  ap- 
proached the  Lord,  and  standing  be- 
side him,  addressed  him  thus: 

"O  Master,  let  the  Lord  now  die 
the  death  of  an  Arahat,8  let  the  Auspi- 
cious One  die  the  death  of  an  Ara- 
hat: now,  O  Master,  is  the  time  for 
the  Lord  to  die  this  death ;  and  more- 
over this  word  was  spoken  by  the 
Lord:  'O  Evil  One,  I  shall  not  die 
the  death  of  an  Arahat  until  my 


8  Parinibbatu,  literally  "become  extinct,"  conveying  the  double  idea  of 
physical  and  passional  death.  See  note  in  Buddhist  and  Christian  Gospels, 
fourth  ed.,  Vol.  II,  p.  99. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  133 

And  Jesus  answering  said  unto  him,  monks  and  nuns,  my  laymen  and 
It  is  said,  Thou  shalt  not  tempt  the  lay-women  become  wise  and  trained 
Lord  thy  God.  disciples,  reciters  of  the  Doctrine, 

walking  in  the  doctrine  and  the  pre- 
cepts, walking  consistently,  living  out 

the  precepts 

"And  now,  Master,  [is  this  the 
case].  O  Master,  let  the  Lord  now 
die  the  death  of  an  Arahat,  let  the 
Auspicious  One  die  the  death  of  an 
Arahat;  now,  O  Master,  is  the  time 
for  the  Lord  to  die  this  death !" 

When  he  had  thus  spoken,  the  Lord 
said  unto  Maro,  the  Evil  One:  "O 
Evil  One,  be  content ;  the  Tathagato's 
Arahat-death  will  not  be  long:  at  the 
end  of  three  months  is  the  time  for 
the  Lord  to  die  the  death  of  an  Ara- 
hat." 

The  Demi  Disappears. 

And  when  the  devil  had  completed 

every  temptation,  he  departed  from      Claf  lfie*  Collectlon    <«   Se1uence 
him  for  a  season.  above)' 

Here  we  have,  in  the  Pali  and  the  Chinese  of  the  Classified 
and  Long  Collections,  representing  two  Buddhist  sects  of  great  an- 
tiquity, the  following  root-ideas: 

1.  Appearance  of  the  Tempter  to  the  Saviour  in  a  wilderness. 

2.  Temptation  to  assume  empire. 

3.  To  use  mystical  power  to  transmute  matter. 

4.  To  commit  suicide. 

5.  Disappearance  of  the  Tempter  when  foiled. 

Now  Luke  has  these  same  root-ideas,  though  expressed  differ- 
ently in  the  third  case  (or,  in  his  text,  the  first)  :  viz.,  the  trans- 
mutation of  stones  into  bread  instead  of  into  gold.  Matthew  also  has 
them,  but  he  interpolates  Luke's  third  temptation  (that  of  suicide) 
between  them.  I  therefore  give  the  text  of  Luke,  because  it  agrees 
with  the  Buddhist  association,  as  Luke  so  often  does.4 

It  is  imperatively  necessary  to  study  these  parallels  by  means 
of  their  earliest  sources ;  viz.,  the  Pali  and  Chinese  Hinayana  texts 

4  See  the  article  Luke  and  Buddhism,  in  the  General  Index  to  the  fourth 
edition  of  Buddhist  and  Christian  Gospels.  Of  course  there  is  the  possibility 
that  the  Temptation  scenes  of  Luke  and  Matthew  (they  are  not  in  Mark, 
though  he  mentions  the  Temptation)  belong  to  a  lost  book  whereto  both  are 
indebted.  I  believe  scholars  generally  consider  that  these  scenes  were  not  in 
the  Logia  source.  My  own  belief  is  that  Luke  was  the  first  to  introduce  them, 
and  the  editor  of  Matthew  adopted  them  from  his  text. 


134  THE  MONIST. 

on  the  one  hand  and  the  Greek  Gospels  on  the  other.  Seydel  made 
the  great  mistake  of  dealing  with  late  books  like  the  Lalita  Vistara, 
without  distinguishing  its  lesser  value  for  the  comparison.  Even  so 
learned  a  scholar  as  Garbe  still  holds  to  the  Seydel  tradition,  and 
consequently  makes  short  work  of  the  Temptation  parallel  by  quot- 
ing these  later  legends  (Monist,  October,  1911,  pp.  517,  518). 

I  maintain  that  there  is  as  much  striking  agreement  between 
Luke  and  the  Hinayana  texts  as  there  is  between  the  Jatakas  and 
the  legends  of  Saints  Christopher  and  Eustace,  except  that  the  latter 
are  much  longer  and  furnish  more  details  for  comparison. 

In  the  temptation  story  there  is  the  same  Christian  coloring  as 
in  the  saint-legends,  and  yet  the  root-ideas  agree.  The  Christian 
coloring  consists  in  making  the  Master  quote  scripture,  whereas 
the  Buddhist  idea  requires  him  to  state  some  truth.  Again  and  again 
in  the  Jatakas  do  we  find  the  same  magical  efficacy  ascribed  to  the 
calm  enunciation  of  a  truth  which  the  Brahmins  ascribe  to  the 
words  of  the  Veda  and  the  Jews  to  those  of  the  Torah.  In  the 
Zend-Avesta  the  Tempter  uses  a  similar  sacred  word,  but,  as  hinted 
elsewhere  (Buddhist  and  Christian  Gospels,  4th  ed.,  Vol.  I,  p.  106), 
the  Mazdean  temptation  story  is  only  like  the  Christian  one  in  its 
theism  and  its  quotation  of  scripture.  The  earliest  account  of  the 
temptation  of  Zoroaster  is  in  the  Vendidad,  and  it  consists  of  only 
one,  viz.,  that  of  empire.  Before  the  temptation  the  fiend  makes  a 
vain  attack  on  the  prophet's  life,  and  after  it  the  prophet  declares 
that  he  will  defeat  the  forces  of  evil  by  two  things: 

1.  The  eucharistic  utensils  and  sacred  drink; 

2.  A  magical  word  taught  him  by  the  Godhead  in  a  past  eternity. 
While  all  this  is  of  fascinating  interest  to  the  student  of  religion 

and  of  the  New  Testament  in  particular,  yet  it  is  by  no  means  so 
close  to  the  Christian  stories  as  are  the  earliest  Buddhist  ones. 

The  Classified  Collection  and  the  Decease  Book  represent  home- 
grown primitive  Buddhism.  And  with  these  does  Luke  agree  rather 
than  with  the  geographically  and  theologically  nearer  Zoroastrian 
account. 

In  two  other  cases  does  Garbe  neglect  important  parallels  from 
the  Pali  Nikayas.  On  page  521  he  gives  us  interesting  evidence, 
from  his  Sanskrit  reading,  of  the  Hindu  character  of  the  idea  of 
walking  upon  the  water,  and  says  (as  since  amended)  that  it  "be- 
longs not  only  to  the  India  of  Budhism,  but  to  that  of  Brahminism 
also."  He  ought  to  have  added  that  the  power  to  walk  on  the  water 
is  among  the  gifts  of  a  pious  Buddhist,  ascribed  to  him  by  Buddha 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  135 

himself,  in  the  sixth  sutra  of  the  Middling  Collection  in  the  Pali 
(No.  105  in  the  Chinese  version  of  A.  D.  397) — a  Hindu  book  far 
older  than  the  Brahmin  Mahabharata  (though  not  of  course  than 
its  ancient  nucleus). 

Again  on  page  517  Professor  Garbe  says:  "Christ  fasts  forty 
days  before  the  Temptation,  Buddha  twenty-eight  days  after  the 
Temptation."  But  in  the  thirty-sixth  sutra  of  the  Middling  Col- 
lection we  read  that  Buddha  fasted  nearly  to  death  before  his 
illumination,  and  therefore  before  his  Temptation,  which  latter  oc- 
curred after  he  was  Bhagava  (the  Lord).5 

No  one  who  studies  the  Periplus  of  the  Erythrcean  Sea,  a  cap- 
tain's log  book  of  the  first  century  (now  newly  translated  by  Wilfred 
H.  Schoff  of  Philadelphia)  will  be  able  to  agree  with  Professor 
Garbe  (p.  524)  in  his  limitation  of  the  probability  of  Indian  in- 
fluence on  Palestine  to  later  times.  The  Periplus  agrees,  for  the 
sixties,  with  Strabo,  who  saw  120  ships  ready  to  sail  from  a  Red 
Sea  port  to  India  in  the  twenties  of  the  first  century.  And,  as  Wil- 
fred Schoff  has  shown  in  his  article  on  another  page  of  this  issue, 
the  Roman  Empire  had  a  sort  of  Indian  craze  at  that  very  time. 

In  Buddhist  and  Christian  Gospels,  the  Lalita  Vistara  and  other 
later  books  are  treated  in  the  Appendix  as  "Uncanonical  Parallels," 
while  the  body  of  the  book  deals  with  canonical  parallels,  translated 
from  the  Pali  texts  by  myself  and  compared  with  the  Chinese  ver- 
sion of  another  ancient  recension  of  the  Buddhist  scriptures  (the 
Hindu  original  of  which  is  lost)  by  Professor  Anesaki  of  Tokyo. 

When  Rhys  Davids's  Buddhist  Suttas  (Sacred  Books  of  the 
East,  Vol.  XI)  were  sent  me  by  my  bookseller  in  1881,  I  found 
therein  a  vigorous  protest  against  any  attempt  to  trace  Buddhist 
loans  in  the  New  Testament.  This  made  a  great  impression  upon 
my  youthful  mind,  and  acted  as  a  deterrent  in  that  direction  until 
nearly  the  end  of  the  century.  Then,  in  1899,  Rendel  Harris 
astonished  me  by  postulating  a  Buddhist  influence  in  the  Acts  of 
Thomas  and  (save  the  mark!)  in  the  Gospel  of  Luke!  I  was 
stunned  at  first,  then  rallied  myself  and  returned  to  my  old  ob- 
jections. During  the  next  seven  years,  however,  deeper  research 
caused  me  to  change ;  and  when  in  1906  I  observed  the  double  quo- 
tation in  John,6  I  admitted  that  here  at  least  was  tangible  influence. 
It  was  anent  the  essay  which  I  then  wrote  that  Rhys  Davids  said 

6  Samyutta  Nikayo,  already  quoted.    Had  the  Temptation  occurred  before 
the  Illumination  we  should  have  read  Bodhisatto. 

'See  "Buddhist  Texts  in  the  Fourth  Gospel,"  Open  Court,  May,  1911. 


136  THE  MONIST. 

to  me :  "The  evidences  in  favor  of  intercommunication  are  growing 
every  day."  (I  asked  his  permission  to  quote  this,  and  he  granted 
it).  Paul  Carus,  in  The  Open  Court,  October,  1911,  has  adduced 
a  remarkable  picture  from  a  Greek  vase,  portraying  a  goddess  with 
water  for  her  lower  body,  and  he  thinks  that  both  the  Buddhist 
and  Johannine  texts  may  be  dependent  upon  some  such  ancient 
idea.  So  they  may,  but  the  strength  of  my  case  lies  in  the  fact  that 
the  Fourth  Gospel's  express  quotations  from  sacred  literature  (Law 
and  Scripture).  Instead  of  admitting  that  the  quotations  are  from 
the  Buddhist  writings,  where  I  have  found  them,  several  of  my 
critics  prefer  to  ascribe  them  to  some  lost  apocryphal  Jewish  book. 
But  the  time  is  rapidly  passing  when  scholars  will  feel  compelled  to 
adopt  any  hypothesis  rather  than  admit  the  greatness  of  ancient 
India  and  the  supremacy  of  Buddhism  which,  at  the  time  of  Christ, 
was  the  most  powerful  religion  on  the  planet  and  the  dominant 
spiritual  force  upon  the  continent  of  Asia. 

In  Buddhist  and  Christian  Gospels  (4th  ed.,  Vol.  II,  p.  237) 
we  read: 

"A  collection  of  [uncanonical]  parallels  would  probably  sug- 
gest a  Christian  influence  upon  later  Buddhism;  and  indeed  we 
know  that,  in  the  eighth  century,  a  Chinese  emperor  had  to  forbid 
the  two  religions  to  be  mixed.  (See  Takakusu's  note  in  his  I-Tsing, 
Oxford,  1896,  p.  224.)  This  whole  field  needs  very  careful  work- 
ing, more  than  I  am  able  to  give." 

Two  Anglican  clergymen,  the  late  Samuel  Beal  and  Arthur 
Lloyd  recently  deceased,  have  maintained  this  position.  The  fact 
is  that  after  Kanishka's  Council  a  new  type  of  Buddhism,  pre- 
dominantly Mahayana,  gradually  supplanted  the  earlier.  This  new 
type  was  largely  foreign,  as  the  primitive  type  had  been  native 
Hindu.  Before  the  Scythian  invasions  at  the  end  of  the  first  cen- 
tury, the  Buddhism  of  Asoka,  with  its  Pali  texts,  had  been  in  the 
ascendant ;  and  as,  in  the  first  century,  Christianity  was  in  a  forma- 
tive stage,  while  Buddhism  was  settled  and  aggressive,  the  loans 
went  from  east  to  west.  But  afterwards  there  was  a  change.  In 
the  first  place,  a  different  race  of  sailors  appeared  in  the  Red  Sea 
ports,7  bearing  with  them  the  newer  Buddhism  which  they  them- 
selves were  helping  to  modify ;  and,  secondly,  Christianity  itself  was 
becoming  a  rival  to  Buddhism,  and  was  beginning  to  assert  itself. 

It  may  be  that  Buddhism  influenced  the  Roman  Empire  by 

7 1  owe  this  information  to  Wilfred  H.  Schoff,  translator  of  the  new  edi- 
tion of  the  Periplus. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  137 

means  of  intermediary  books,  such  as  that  of  Elkesai  which  had  a 
confessedly  Buddhist  origin  ("Seres  of  Parthia")  ;  but  I  maintain 
that  the  Nikayas  of  primitive  Buddhism  were  strong  enough  to 
make  themselves  felt  more  directly.  In  A.  D.  149  a  Parthian  prince 
headed  a  long  series  of  scholars  who  translated  them  into  Chinese; 
but  Buddhism  had  been  established  in  the  Greek  empire  (Yona- 
loko)  since  the  third  century  B.  C,  and  was  quoted,  chapter  and 
verse,8  by  a  Greek  king,  Menander,  in  the  second.  Now,  the 
Chinese  began  to  translate  Buddhist  books  immediately  upon  that 
religion's  introduction  into  their  country  in  the  sixties  of  the  first 
century ;  and  after  a  generation  or  two  of  translating  manuals,  lives 
of  Buddha  etc.,  they  spent  three  centuries  (circa  1 50-450 )9  in  trans- 
lating the  Nikayas  (or  Agamas).  Were  the  Greeks  less  curious 
than  the  Chinese?  Had  not  they  also  begun  to  translate  the  books 
they  admired  long  before  the  time  of  Christ  ?  My  thesis  is  this  :10 

While  a  religion  is  in  its  formative  stage,  its  founders  take  ideas 
from  their  environment,  and  especially  from  any  system  of  thought 
that  is  paramount,  whether  in  their  own  country  or  in  those  where- 
with they  have  intercourse.  But,  once  knit  together,  and  moving 
by  its  own  momentum,  a  religion  can  no  longer  add  to  its  primitive 
documents,  though  it  may  give  way  to  new  influences  in  later  sec- 
tarian developments. 

The  thesis  applied  is  this : 

During  the  first  century  Christianity  was  in  its  formative  stage, 
and  was  influenced  by  the  Old  Testament,  the  Greek  mysteries,  the 
Philonic  philosophy  and  by  Hinayana  Buddhism.  After  the  first 
century  Christianity  was  strong  enough  to  influence  another  religion 
in  its  formative  stage.  And  such  was  Mahayana  Buddhism,  which 
was,  in  fact,  a  new  religion,  with  new  doctrines  and  new  sacred 
books.  At  the  same  time,  Hinayana  Buddhism  still  existed,  and  indeed 
its  votaries  often  cultivated  the  Mahayana  too.  Consequently  there 
could  be  and  there  was  a  complex  interchange  between  Christianity 
and  Buddhism,  both  of  them  giving  and  taking.  But  the  earliest 
interchange  was  when  the  Hellenizing  Evangelists  Luke  and  John 
borrowed  some  minor  features  from  the  Hinayana  Nikayas,  then 
in  the  ascendant. 

Before  closing,  let  me  add  a  note  on  the  Wandering  Jew  legend 

8  So  in  the  Pali,  though  Chinese  versions  do  not  bear  it  out. 

9  Anesaki  in  Transactions  of  the  Asiatic  Society  of  Japan,  1908,  p.  15. 

18  See  my  remarks  on  the  Imperfection  of  the  Record  (following  Darwin) 
in  Buddhist  Texts  in  John  (2d  ed.,  1911,  p.  27). 


138  THE  MONIST. 

among  the  "Uncanonical  Parallels"  in  my  Buddhist  and  Christian 
Gospels.  I  lately  learned  that  Sabine  Baring-Gould  in  1866  pointed 
out  that  the  germ  of  the  legend  is  actually  found  in  the  canonical 
Gospels : 

Mark  ix.  1 :  "Verily  I  say  unto  you,  There  be  some  here  of  them 
that  stand  by,  who  shall  in  no  wise  taste  of  death,  till  they  see  the 
Kingdom  of  God  come  with  power." 

Let  me  repeat  what  I  said  last  May  in  The  Open  Court,  and 
which  Professor  Garbe  does  me  the  honor  to  quote:  Each  religion 
is  independent  in  the  main,  but  the  younger  one  arose  in  such  a 
hotbed  of  eclecticism  that  it  probably  borrowed  a  few  legends  and 
ideas  from  the  older,  which  was  quite  accessible  to  it.  The  loans 
are  not  an  integral  part  of  primitive  Christian  doctrine,  as  I  said 
in  my  Tokyo  preface  (1905),  but  lie  outside  of  the  Synoptical  narra- 
tive, and  occur  in  the  two  later  Gospels  of  Luke  and  John,  both  open 
to  Gentile  influences. 

Even  now  I  only  put  forth  these  parallels  upon  the  same  footing 
as  Gaster,  Speyer  and  Garbe's  Christopher  and  Eustace;  and  if  the 
scholars  of  Europe  and  Asia  finally  decide  that  they  are  wrong,  I 
shall  withdraw  my  venture  with  a  good  grace.  But  if  this  great 
admission  of  Buddhist  influence  upon  the  Christian  Apocryphal 
Gospels  and  the  Eustace  and  Christopher  legends  receives  its  "brevet 
of  orthodoxy/'  the  next  step  will  lead  a  new  generation  of  scholars 
back  to  the  canonical  Gospels  and  the  canonical  Nikayas. 

ALBERT  J.  EDMUNDS. 

PHILADELPHIA,  PA. 


FIRST  CENTURY  INTERCOURSE  BETWEEN  INDIA  AND 

ROME. 

EDMUNDS  VS.   GARBE. 

In  The  Monist  for  October,  1911,  appears  a  paper  by  Prof. 
Richard  Garbe  of  Tubingen  entitled  "Contributions  of  Buddhism  to 
Christianity,"  the  essence  of  which  is  that  common  material  is  found 
in  the  Apocryphal  writings  of  both  religions,  but  that  no  connection 
can  be  proved  between  the  Canonical  texts,  and  that  this  is  due  to 
the  fact  that  active  intercommunication  between  India  and  the  Medi- 
terranean did  not  exist  until  the  second  century,  or,  as  Professor 
Garbe  puts  it,  "Buddhist  influence  might  have  penetrated  to  Pales- 
tine by  way  of  Alexandria,  but  still  more  probably  by  way  of 
Antioch  in  Syria,  but  they"  (that  is,  writers  pointing  out  similari- 


CRITICISMS   AND   DISCUSSIONS.  139 

ties)  "are  not  apt  to  raise  this  possibility  to  a  serviceable  degree 
of  probability  for  as  early  a  period  as  the  first  post-Christian  cen- 
tury." 

In  thus  denying  the  existence  of  a  rapidly  growing  and  very 
important  stream  of  commerce  between  India  and  Rome,  it  seems 
evident  that  Professor  Garbe  has  overlooked  historical  facts  which, 
if  duly  recognized,  may  compel  him  to  revise  his  opinion  in  this 
matter  as  he  changed  his  mind  in  regard  to  the  migration  of  the 
fish-symbol  from  India  to  Rome. 

The  incontestable  facts  of  history  are  that  a  large  Indian  in- 
fluence and  an  active  commerce  existed  as  far  as  the  Mediterranean 
coast  of  Syria  soon  after  the  conquests  of  Alexander,  and  that  the 
conquest  of  these  territories  by  Roman  armies  ending  in  the  public 
triumphs  of  Pompey  the  Great,  created  in  the  Roman  capital  a  craze 
for  Indian  products  and  luxuries  of  all  kinds  which  during  the 
actual  lifetime  of  Christ  had  become  a  serious  problem  to  the  Roman 
government,  leading  to  numerous  efforts  at  discouragement  of  the 
taste  for  Eastern  luxuries  which  was  draining  the  Empire  of  its 
resources.  This  craze  met  with  a  temporary  check  at  the  death  of 
Nero.  It  regained  full  intensity  under  Trajan  and  Hadrian,  and 
was  again  in  a  decline  during  a  considerable  part  of  the  second 
Christian  century,  reviving  during  the  reign  of  Commodus,  and 
again  more  seriously  declining  with  the  failing  powers  of  the  Em- 
pire. The  existence  of  this  craze  for  Indian  imports  and  of  the 
substantial  remittances  of  gold  coin  required  to  balance  the  trade, 
may  be  surely  proved  by  the  hoards  of  Roman  coin  unearthed  in 
Southern  India  and  catalogued  by  the  Government  Museum  at 
Madras ;  in  which  these  fluctuating  eras  of  trade  prosperity  and 
depression  clearly  appear.  Instead,  therefore,  of  the  creation  of  a 
new  import  trade  from  India  in  the  second  century,  as  Professor 
Garbe  asserts,  the  most  active  trade  was  in  the  first  half  of  the  first 
century,  with  two  revivals  at  the  beginning  and  the  end  respectively 
of  the  second ;  and  the  drain  of  specie  from  Rome  to  the  East  had 
set  in  even  before  the  birth  of  Christ. 

Space  forbids  a  statement  in  detail  of  the  almost  innumerable 
facts  existing  to  support  the  foregoing  statement.  The  following 
may  at  least  serve  as  suggestions. 

Alexander  married  a  Persian  princess,  but  numbers  of  his 
officers  took  Bactrian  and  Indian  wives. 

Greek  colonies  were  established  by  him  along  the  entire  Indian 
frontier,  and  colonies  of  his  newly  established  Indian  subjects  were 


I4O  THE  MONIST. 

similarly  established  nearer  Greece.  A  Greek  dynasty  ruled  in 
Bactria  after  the  Parthian  revolt  disrupted  the  Seleucid  empire,  and 
one  of  its  rulers,  Menander,  powerfully  influenced  the  spread  of 
Buddhist  thought  through  the  Greek-speaking  world. 

A  Greek  ambassador  at  the  Maurya  court,  Megasthenes,  wrote 
a  detailed  account  of  its  customs,  its  Brahmin  religion,  and  its  cap- 
ital Pataliputra;  which  was  widely  read  and  commented  upon  for 
centuries. 

The  conquest  of  Judea  by  the  Persians  and  the  destruction  of 
the  Persian  empire  by  Alexander,  reduced  the  force  of  Judaism  and 
Mazdaism  as  world-religions,  while  the  exodus  of  the  Greeks  into 
the  East  broke  down  what  was  left  of  the  distinctive  Greek  religion. 
There  existed  then  no  faith  strongly  upheld  in  the  Eastern  Medi- 
terranean basin  from  the  third  to  the  first  centuries  B.  C. 

Two  generations  after  Alexander's  conquests,  the  Emperor 
Asoka  established  Buddhism  as  the  state  religion  of  India,  and  in 
his  second  edict,  preserved  to  us  in  a  rock  inscription,  he  mentions 
the  sending  of  envoys  to  all  countries  with  which  he  entertained 
relations ;  particularly  mentioning  "the  dominions  of  the  Greek  king 
Antiochus,  and  those  of  the  other  kings  subordinate  to  that  An- 
tiochus." This  ruler  is  identified  with  Antiochus  Theos  (B.  C.  261- 
246)  in  whose  capital  of  Antioch  these  Indian  envoys,  physicians 
and  missionaries,  for  they  seem  to  have  held  that  triple  character, 
were  received.  In  the  capital  of  that  ruler  who  profaned  the  Jewish 
Holy  of  Holies  in  order  to  set  up  the  worship  of  himself,  the  Bud- 
dhist faith  was  preached  by  men  sent  from  the  head  of  the  Buddhist 
organization,  the  ruler  of  the  richest,  most  powerful  and  most  popu- 
lous empire  in  the  world  at  that  time. 

During  the  better  days  of  the  Seleucidae,  overland  communica- 
tion between  India  and  Syria  was  unhampered,  and  there  is  every 
indication  that  it  carried  an  active  commerce.  The  fall  of  the  Se- 
leucid power  and  the  rise  of  the  Parthian  monarchy  interposed  a 
fiscal  obstruction  which  the  Greek  rulers  in  Egypt,  the  Ptolemies, 
quickly  turned  to  their  advantage.  By  the  establishment  of  ports 
on  the  Red  Sea,  Egyptian  shipping  was  enabled  to  trade  in  the  Gulf 
of  Aden  and  obtain  Indian  merchandise  with  less  transshipment 
than  had  formerly  been  made,  and  the  opulence  of  this  trade  is 
vividly  described  by  Agatharchides,  writing  in  the  closing  years 
of  the  second  century  B.  C. 

For  two  centuries  following  Alexander's  death  we  may  assume 
that  the  Indian  trade  went  no  further  than  the  Eastern  Mediter- 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  141 

ranean ;  but  the  rise  of  Rome  as  a  world-power,  dating  finally  from 
the  sack  of  Carthage  and  Corinth  in  146  B.  C,  brought  the  Romans 
into  active  trade  with  the  Levantine  ports,  as  evidenced  by  the  growth 
of  piracy  in  that  region,  preying  on  the  Roman  ships.  Pompey's 
contributions  to  the  Roman  state  were  the  suppression  of  the  pirates 
and  the  conquest  of  the  Levant ;  and  in  his  triumphal  processions, 
which  are  repeatedly  mentioned  by  Pliny  in  his  "Natural  History," 
all  the  more  precious  varieties  of  Indian  merchandise  were  exhibited 
and  brought  into  popular  demand.  This  point  is  of  importance. 
Two  generations  before  the  birth  of  Christ  the  spoils  of  a  conquered 
land  resulted  in  a  fashion  for  the  imports  of  that  land  rather  than 
for  its  own  products:  for  the  Indian  goods  transshipped  at  the 
Syrian  ports,  rather  than  for  the  products  of  Syria  itself.  The  Indian 
trade  had  become  Syria's  richest  asset. 

The  same  facts  are  in  evidence  upon  the  conquest  of  Egypt  and 
the  incorporation  of  the  Alexandrian  trade  into  the  Roman  fiscal 
system.  Primarily  grain  was  the  staple  export  from  Egypt  to  Rome, 
but  the  more  profitable  trade  consisted  in  the  incense  of  Arabia  and 
the  gems  and  spices  and  textiles  of  India. 

In  22  A.  D.,  in  a  letter  from  the  Emperor  Tiberius  to  the 
Roman  Senate  set  forth  by  Tacitus  in  his  "Annals,"  the  growing 
drain  of  specie  is  pointed  out  and  a  remedy  demanded.  "How," 
said  the  Emperor,  "are  we  to  deal  with  the  peculiar  articles  of  fem- 
inine vanity,  and  in  particular  with  that  rage  for  jewels  and  precious 
trinkets,  which  drains  the  Empire  of  its  wealth  and  sends,  in  ex- 
change for  baubles,  the  money  of  the  Commonwealth  to  foreign 
nations;  even  the  enemies  of  Rome?" 

The  geographer  Strabo,  writing  in  almost  the  same  year,  records 
having  seen  a  single  fleet  of  120  ships  about  to  start  by  the  favorable 
monsoon  from  an  Egyptian  Red  Sea  port  to  India.  Two  genera- 
tions later,  according  to  Pliny,  the  unfavorable  trade-balance  had 
grown  more  serious  still ;  as  he  says  "in  no  year  does  India  drain 
us  of  less  than  550,000,000  sesterces,  giving  back  her  own  wares, 
which  are  sold  among  us  at  fully  100  times  their  first  cost." 

550,000,000  sesterces  in  those  days  was  a  very  considerable 
sum.  In  modern  valuation  it  would  approach  $25,000,000,  and  this 
was  the  state  of  affairs  existing  at  the  end  of  the  reign  of  Nero. 
Can  one  imagine  a  modern  trade  requiring  so  enormous  an  export 
of  specie  without  a  corresponding  influx  of  merchants,  bearing 
ideas  no  less  than  goods,  from  the  producing  to  the  purchasing 
market?  This  condition  is  indeed  set  forth  with  sufficient  exactness 


142  THE  MONIST. 

by  the  writer  of  the  Apocalypse,  where  he  describes,  under  a  veil 
of  fiction,  the  burning  of  Rome  and  the  ruin  that  thereby  came  upon 
"every  ship-master  and  all  the  company  in  ships,  and  sailors,  and 
as  many  as  trade  by  sea,"  while  of  the  merchandise  they  handled  are 
specified  numerous  Indian  products,  precious  stones,  pearls,  silk, 
ivory,  fragrant  wood,  iron  (Indian  steel  was  known  even  to  the 
Greeks),  cinnamon,  odors,  ointments.  This  was  in  64  A.  D.  A 
year  or  two  before,  according  to  Pliny,  at  the  funeral  of  Nero's  con- 
sort Poppsea,  there  was  burned  a  store  of  Eastern  spices  representing 
a  year's  imports  and  valued  at  millions. 

The  unknown  merchant  of  this  same  period  who  has  left  us 
that  interesting  log  of  his  trading  voyages  from  Roman  Egypt  to 
India  which  we  know  as  the  "Periplus  of  the  Erythrsean  Sea/'1 
enters  more  specifically  into  the  various  articles  dealt  in  and  the 
marked  growth  in  the  trade.  Briefly  following  him  along  his 
voyage,  at  the  lower  western  shore  of  the  Red  Sea  were  imported 
Indian  iron  and  steel,  Indian  cloth,  muslin  and  lac.  On  the  oppo- 
site shore,  at  the  Arabian  side  of  the  straits,  was  a  special  port 
established  for  incoming  Indian  ships,  which  were  apparently  for- 
bidden to  trade  by  the  Arabs'  port  of  Muza.  On  the  outer  coast, 
which  we  know  as  Somaliland,  Indian  cinnamon  was  found  and 
ships  of  larger  size  were  now  required  to  handle  it.  Other  Indian 
gums  are  specified,  among  them  gum  dammar,  and  an  Indian  rem- 
edy for  tropical  disorders,  macir,  which  does  not  again  appear  in 
western  commercial  annals  until  the  days  of  the  Portuguese.  At 
Cape  Guardafui  was  a  regular  trading  rendezvous  to  which  came 
numerous  ships  from  the  Gulf  of  Cambay  bringing  cereals,  clari- 
fied butter,  sesame  oil,  cotton  goods,  and  honey  from  the  reed  called 
"sacchari" ;  the  first  known  record  of  sugar  as  an  article  of  com- 
merce. 

On  the  southern  coast  of  Arabia  were  two  ports  at  which  In- 
dian shipping  regularly  called.  At  the  one  Roman  coral,  tin,  cop- 
per and  storax  were  transshipped  for  the  Indian  trade,  and  at  the 
other,  more  to  the  east,  Indian  shipping  often  wintered.  Proceed- 
ing with  our  merchant  to  the  mouth  of  the  Indus,  we  find  these 
same  Roman  products  recorded  among  the  imports  of  Northwestern 
India  including,  strange  to  say,  Italian  wines,  preferred  to  the  Syr- 
ian, or  Arabian;  all  of  which  were  imported.  At  the  port  of  Bary- 
gaza  in  the  Gulf  of  Cambay,  the  newly  established  Saka  government 

*A  new  translation,  with  learned  notes,  of  this  document  is  listed  by 
Longmans  for  1912.    The  translator  is  the  writer  of  this  article. — ED. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  143 

maintained  a  regular  system  of  pilotage  which  was  necessary  to 
avoid  destruction  of  foreign  vessels  by  the  tremendous  tides  of  that 
estuary.  These  pilot-boats  coasted  the  shores  of  the  Gulf  for  100 
miles  outside  the  port,  and  our  merchant  records  that  both  Greek 
and  Arabian  shipping  was  guided  by  them.  Here  he  found  among 
other  things,  spikenard,  highly  treasured  in  the  ointments  of  the 
time  as  appears  in  the  Gospel  of  Mark,  chap.  xiv.  3-5 ;  and  more 
important  still,  murrhine,  that  Indian  carnelian,  its  colors  heightened 
by  slow  heat  and  shaped  into  drinking  vessels  for  which,  according 
to  Pliny,  fabulous  sums  were  paid  in  Rome.  Petronius  broke  one 
of  Nero's  basins  valued  at  300,000  sesterces,  while  Nero  himself 
paid  one  million  sesterces  for  a  single  cup.  Here  at  Barygaza  were 
also  imported  for  the  Indian  markets  Italian  wine,  copper,  tin  and 
lead  for  the  coinage  of  the  country,  coral  and  topaz,  storax  for  the 
Chinese  trade,  glass,  gold  and  silver  coin  on  which  there  was  a 
profit  when  exchanged  for  the  money  of  the  kingdom, — the  Roman 
coinage  being  superior  to  the  Hindu,  which  was  of  base  metals 
only,  while  the  Roman  gold  coin  formed  the  standard  of  exchange 
for  all  the  nations  of  India.  Further  down  the  coast  in  the  back 
waters  of  Cochin  and  Travancore  he  found  especially  pepper  and 
malabathrum  (cinnamon  leaves),  on  account  of  the  great  quantity 
and  bulk  of  which  our  merchant  tells  us,  large  ships  were  sent  to 
those  ports,  Greek  and  Arabian  as  well  as  Hindu.  Here  were  found 
also  great  quantities  of  fine  pearls,  ivory  and  precious  stones,  beryls, 
diamonds  and  sapphires,  and  tortoise-shell,  coming  from  as  far  dis- 
tant as  the  Straits  of  Malacca  in  ships  specially  recorded  as  "of  great 
size"  in  comparison  with  those  Roman  ships  with  which  our  author 
was  familiar.  In  the  adjoining  nation,  easily  recognizable  as  the 
Chola  Kingdom,  whose  capital  Uraiyur  (Trichinopoly)  is  recog- 
nizable under  the  author's  corruption  of  Argaru,  were  found  in 
profusion  all  the  merchandise  sent  from  Egypt ;  while  its  ports  were 
a  center  of  shipping  not  only  from  Egypt  but  from  the  Ganges  and 
Malacca.  Here  our  author  digresses  to  mention  Chinese  silk  brought 
overland  through  Bactria  to  Western  India  for  reshipment  to  the 
Roman  empire,  and  among  the  exports  from  Rome  to  balance  this 
trade  is  again  mentioned  "a  great  quantity  of  coin,"  fully  support- 
ing the  testimony  of  the  hoards  unearthed  in  Southern  India  and 
recorded  at  Madras.  The  coins  of  Claudius  and  Nero  are  among 
the  most  numerous  of  all  discovered. 

The  word  which  the  author  of  the  Periplus  uses  for  the  palm 
oil  found  by  him  at  Zanzibar,  was  a  word  brought  from  India,  the 


144  THE  MONIST. 

Prakrit  nargil,  coconut.  The  most  authentic  information  at  the 
disposal  of  Lieutenant  Speke  in  preparing  for  his  expedition  for  the 
discovery  of  the  sources  of  the  Nile,  was  a  map  based  on  the  Hindu 
Puranas,  and  setting  forth  information  brought  by  these  same  In- 
dian vessels  found  by  the  merchant  of  the  Periplus  on  the  African 
coast.  These  traders  had  penetrated  the  interior  and  knew  of  the 
Nyanza  lakes,  as  the  Egyptians  did  not.  The  facts  already  cited 
are  surely  sufficient  to  show  a  volume  of  trade  not  only  inter- 
nationally important,  but  so  great  and  so  one-sided  as  to  be  recog- 
nized as  a  serious  menace  to  the  prosperity  of  the  newer,  poorer, 
and  less  populous  empire  of  the  West. 

Petronius,  Nero's  crony  whom  Pliny  connects  with  the  mad 
auction  of  murrhine  cups,  has  left  us  Trimalchio's  Dinner,  that  in- 
imitable sketch  of  parvenu  society  in  Rome  at  the  middle  of  the 
first  Christian  century,  in  which  it  is  mentioned  as  a  matter  of  course 
that  a  rich  man  sent  to  India  for  so  slight  a  thing  as  mushroom 
spawn.  Pliny  tells  how  Lollia  Paulina,  wife  of  the  Emperor  Ca- 
ligula, wore  at  an  ordinary  betrothal  entertainment  emeralds  and 
pearls  to  the  value  of  40,000,000  sesterces;  "indeed,  she  was  pre- 
pared to  prove  the  fact  by  showing  the  receipts  and  acquittances." 
And  he  goes  on  to  bemoan  the  prodigality  in  the  use  of  Indian 
pearls  by  Roman  women ;  "now,  at  the  present  day"  (about  70 
A.  D.)  "the  poorer  classes  are  even  affecting  them....  they  put 
them  on  their  feet,  not  only  on  the  laces  but  all  over  the  shoes;  it 
is  not  enough  to  wear  pearls  but  they  must  tread  upon  them." 

The  author  of  the  Periplus  tells  how  the  Indian  trade,  as  far 
as  western  shipping  at  least  was  concerned,  used  to  be  done  in  small 
vessels  close  to  shore;  and  how  Hippalus  "by  observing  the  loca- 
tion of  the  ports  and  the  conditions  of  the  sea,  discovered  how  to 
lay  his  course  straight  across  the  ocean" — the  monsoon  being  called 
the  "wind  of  Hippalus" — so  that  from  that  time  ships  steered 
direct  from  the  Gulf  of  Aden  and  Cape  Guardafui  to  the  ports  of 
India,  "holding  their  course  straight  out  to  sea  with  a  favorable 
wind,  quite  away  from  the  land."  This  discovery  of  Hippalus  oc- 
curred in  the  time  of  Claudius,  and  the  resulting  increase  of  trade 
culminated  under  Nero.  Pliny  recounts  the  same  story. 

The  distinction  made  by  Professor  Garbe  between  the  paral- 
lelisms in  the  Canonical  texts  and  those  in  the  Apocrypha  points 
to  a  period  of  change  in  the  national  and  religious  politics  of  India 
which  is  apparently  not  realized,  and  is  yet  of  importance  in  the 
study  of  the  interrelations  between  East  and  West.  At  the  be- 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  145 

ginning  of  the  second  century  came  the  Council  of  Kanishka,  the 
Scythian  conqueror  of  the  northwest,  the  second  great  Buddhist 
Council.  The  Scythians  were  looked  upon  askance  by  the  native 
Hindus.  It  is  recorded  in  the  annals  of  the  Andhra  dynasty  that 
after  a  victory  over  the  Scythian  or  Kushan  dominion,  a  memorial 
was  set  up  at  Karli  telling  how  the  orthodox  Andhra  king  had 
"destroyed  the  Sakas,  Yavanas  and  Pahlavas,  properly  expended 
the  taxes  levied  in  accordance  with  the  sacred  law,  and  prevented 
the  mixing  of  the  four  castes."  A  schism  was  thus  set  up  in  India, 
racial  rather  than  religious  at  its  root,  which  later  expanded  into 
the  great  division  between  the  early  Buddhist  canon  and  its  Maha- 
yana  corruptions.  It  was  the  earlier  Buddhism  which  was  carried 
to  the  Syrian  coast  by  the  messengers  of  Asoka.  It  was  still  a 
conservative  Buddhism,  but  mingled  with  various  central  Asian 
religions,  which  was  carried  to  the  same  region  by  the  subjects  of 
Kanishka;  while  the  great  changes  of  the  succeeding  centuries 
brought  into  Buddhism,  no  less  than  into  Christianity,  a  mass  of 
childish  apocryphal  legends  which  passed  from  one  faith  to  the  other 
in  much  the  same  way  as  the  earlier  ideas,  which  to  some  extent  at 
least  are  found  paralleled  in  the  Canonical  texts.  The  distinction  is 
important ;  but  it  is  a  distinction  based  on  changed  national  politics, 
rather  than  newly  created  trade,  as  Professor  Garbe  would  infer. 
This  change  at  the  coming  of  the  Scythian  shipping  into  the  Indian 
Ocean  is  vaguely  indicated  by  Pausanias  in  a  passage  not  usually 
understood,  where  he  speaks  of  the  Island  of  Seria  (which  was 
really  Masira  off  the  Southern  coast  of  Oman)  but  which  he  con- 
fuses with  the  Seres  of  China.  He  tells  us  that  "both  the  Seres  and 
the  inhabitants  of  the  neighboring  islands  of  Abasa  and  Sacsea  [the 
modern  Kuria  Muria]  are  of  the  Ethiopian  race.  Some  say,  how- 
ever, that  they  are  not  Ethiopians  but  a  mixture  of  Scythians  and 
Indians." 

At  that  ancient  meeting-point  between  the  Nile  trade  and  that 
of  the  Indian  Ocean,  the  Abyssinian  highlands,  the  author  of  the 
Periplus  gives  us  the  first  mention  of  the  Kingdom  of  Abyssinia, 
then  newly  established,  and  of  its  capital,  "the  city  of  the  people  called 
Axumites."  The  great  series  of  monoliths  at  Axum  dates  probably 
from  the  first  century  rather  than  the  second  and  shows  orthodox 
early  Buddhist  influence  rather  than  the  Buddhism  of  later  ages. 
James  Fergusson's  description  of  the  great  monolith  has  not  been 
bettered,  "the  idea  Egyptian  but  the  details  Indian,  an  Indian  nine- 
storied  pagoda  translated  in  Egyptian  in  the  first  century  of  the 


146  THE  MONIST. 

Christian  era."  He  notes  its  likeness  to  such  temples  as  the  Bodh 
Gaya,  and  says  it  "represents  that  curious  marriage  of  Indian  with 
Egyptian  art  which  we  should  expect  to  find  in  the  spot  where  the 
two  peoples  came  in  contact  and  enlisted  architecture  to  symbolize 
their  commercial  union."  And  so  obviously  Hindu  a  ceremony  as  the 
Brahman's  investiture  with  the  sacred  cord  is 'still  preserved  as  the 
sign  of  baptism  in  Abyssinian  Christianity. 

Now  the  very  existence  of  the  Abyssinian  state  in  the  beginning 
was  dependent  upon  the  alliance  of  the  Romans  in  Egypt,  who  en- 
couraged its  growth  in  order  to  counteract  the  Arabian  domination 
of  the  Red  Sea  trade;  and  this  was  originally  a  matter  of  first- 
century  diplomacy,  culminating  with  the  decay  of  the  ancient  Sa- 
baean  capital  Marib,  and  the  conquest  of  the  Nabatsean  kingdom 
under  Trajan. 

While  these  relations  between  India  and  the  West  were  being 
developed,  a  similar  connection  was  formed  with  the  East.  The 
silk-market  of  the  world  was  in  a  fertile  valley  of  the  Pamirs,  whither 
Chinese  merchants  brought  their  goods  by  the  great  Pei-lu  or 
"Southern  way"  along  the  desert  of  Turkestan.  Nomadic  marauders 
hampered  the  trade,  so  that  the  author  of  the  Periplus  remarked  of 
China  that  "few  men  come  from  there  and  seldom";  but  the  armies 
of  Pan-Chao  forged  the  last  link  of  the  great  chain,  and  before  the 
end  of  the  first  century  communication  was  unbroken  from  the 
English  Channel  to  the  Yellow  Sea,  and  the  tin  of  Cornwall  ex- 
changed for  the  silk  of  Ts'in. 

We  are  therefore  forced  to  the  conclusion  that  the  middle  of  the 
first  century  of  the  Christian  era  was  a  time  of  unexampled  com- 
mercial activity  between  East  and  West,  that  political  turmoil 
both  in  Rome  and  India  then  caused  a  lull  in  this  traffic,  which  did 
not  fully  revive  until  the  later  years  of  the  second  century,  and  that 
Professor  Garbe's  argument,  in  so  far  as  it  affects  the  general  inter- 
relation between  Buddhism  and  Christianity,  is  to  that  extent  in 
need  of  revision. 

A  Freeman  could  write  "our  business  is  with  Europe,  and  with 
other  parts  of  the  world  only  so  far  as  they  concern  Europe."  And 
the  Christian  Gospels  have  been  read  with  Western  eyes.  The  Holy 
Land  out  of  which  they  came  has  been  conceived  as  a  sort  of  Ultima 
Thule,  beyond  which  lay  a  great  void;  the  country  beyond  Jordan 
being  remembered  as  a  wilderness,  wherein  One  was  tempted  of 
the  devil.  A  barrier  is  thus  set  up  and  maintained,  artificial  and 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  147 

without  foundation,  the  defence  of  which  some  would  assert  to  be  a 
condition  of  right  belief. 

For  some  reason  this  type  of  critic  would  deny  that  an  influx 
of  new  commodities  carried  with  it  a  renascence  of  ideas,  and  would 
draw  the  old  line  about  Christianity,  limiting  its  environments  to  the 
country  this  side  Jordan ;  inevitably  admitting  the  larger  expression 
which  it  received  from  the  Gentile  peoples  of  the  northern  coast 
of  the  Mediterranean,  but  ignoring  that  which  came  from  the  Gen- 
tile peoples  beyond  the  Euphrates  and  the  "Erythraean  Sea."  It  is 
difficult  to  understand  what  is  gained  by  so  obviously  tearing  Chris- 
tianity half  out  by  the  roots.  The  new  faith  reached  out  toward 
the  East  no  less  than  toward  the  North  and  the  West,  and  was  so 
formulated  as  to  be  understood  by  all, — to  be  part  and  parcel  of  the 
intellectual  environment  of  all.  It  would  therefore  be  almost  a 
matter  of  course  that  Christianity,  making  its  appeal  in  the  centers 
of  trade,  at  the  terminus  of  the  great  commercial  highways  from  the 
East,  should  express  its  message  in  terms  likely  to  be  understood 
by  those  acknowledging  Buddhism,  the  faith  of  the  countries  at  the 
eastern  terminus  of  those  highways,  and  of  all  the  world's  faiths 
at  that  time,  unquestionably  the  most  influential. 

Of  lasting  value,  therefore,  are  all  works  which  help  to  break 
down  and  destroy  the  ancient  but  artificial  barriers  between  East 
and  West;  and  of  such  works  a  very  notable  one  is  by  Mr.  Albert 
J.  Edmunds,  Buddhist  and  Christian  Gospels  Now  First  Compared 
from  the  Originals  (Philadelphia,  4th  edition,  1908-09). 

Mr.  Edmunds's  work  goes  back  to  the  age  in  which  the  Gos- 
pels were  formulated,  and  reconstructs  the  background  of  world- 
thought  and  politics  of  which  they  have  been  so  generally  deprived. 

It  is  necessary  to  a  clear  understanding  of  the  Christian  religion 
that  a  painstaking  study  be  made  of  its  points  of  contact  with  the 
Buddhist,  and  of  the  many  thoughts  which  are  their  common  prop- 
erty. Such  a  study  can  detract  from  neither  faith,  but  must  rather 
serve  both,  by  showing  more  fully  the  human  ideas  and  aspirations 
out  of  which  they  arose;  by  showing  them  to  be  living  realities  in 
the  upward  path  of  mankind,  rather  than  abstractions  limited  each 
to  its  own  area.  It  remains  for  the  individual  to  make  his  choice 
between  the  two,  but  he  must  no  longer  be  hedged  in  by  an  arti- 
ficial barrier,  which  for  centuries  has  separated  peoples  closely  re- 
lated at  the  Christian  era,  and  now  by  the  march  of  events,  once 
more  brought  into  contact.  It  is  no  longer  possible  for  the  Teuton 
to  hold  aloof  from  the  Tartar,  the  Anglo-Saxon  from  the  Japanese; 


148  THE  MONIST. 

mutual  interest  requires  a  closer  understanding,  a  readier  sym- 
pathy, and  a  fuller  acknowledgment  of  common  aspirations.  Pres- 
ent-day commerce  has  its  influence  in  this  direction,  and  history 
likewise;  but  sympathetic  comparison  of  the  religions  of  the  two 
races  is  among  the  most  important  of  all  such  influences. 

This  work  by  Mr.  Edmunds  is  therefore  especially  timely,  and 
the  ripe  learning  which  he  brings  to  this  great  subject  assures  its 
permanence. 

Previous  comparisons,  such  as  those  of  Hardy  and  Seydel,  had 
depended  on  translations  and  secondary  authorities  and  had  neces- 
sarily confused  primitive  writings  with  commentary  and  patristics, 
sometimes  of  late  date ;  while  Mr.  Edmunds  works  with  the  advan- 
tage of  an  intimate  knowledge  of  both  the  Pali  and  Greek  originals. 
He  has  limited  himself  to  parallels  occurring  only  in  the  primitive 
writings  of  either  religion,  and  his  presentment  is  most  convincing. 
The  facts  of  history  would  naturally  lead  the  open-minded  investi- 
gator to  look  for  a  certain  parallelism  growing  out  of  this  ancient 
culture-field,  but  hardly  to  expect  so  formidable  a  list  as  102  paral- 
lels of  word  or  thought  in  the  Canonical  writings  and  13  more  in 
the  books  relegated  to  the  Apocrypha,  but  of  early  date,  in  both 
religions.  Furthermore,  as  Mr.  Edmunds  has  shown  in  another 
place  (Buddhist  Texts  in  John,  see  also  Open  Court,  May,  1911) 
Buddhist  writings  are  actually  twice  quoted  as  scripture  in  the 
Christian  Gospel  of  John.  The  proof  of  intercommunication  is 
abundant. 

Mr.  Edmunds's  comparisons  provide  a  rich  field  of  information 
for  the  student  of  comparative  religion,  and  his  conclusion  is  con- 
servative enough  to  satisfy  scholars  of  every  kind.  "No  borrowing 
is  alleged  on  either  side — Christian  or  Buddhist.  In  these  parallels 
we  offer  no  theory  but  present  them  as  facts.  They  at  least  belong 
to  a  world  of  thought  which  the  whole  East  had  in  common." 

Were  it  necessary,  many  other  facts  in  the  history  of  Syria  and 
Palestine  might  be  cited  in  support  of  Mr.  Edmunds's  argument. 
The  Persianizing  tendencies  in  the  later  Jewish  church,  due  to  the 
captivity  in  the  Empire  of  Cyrus,  are  well  known,  while  recent 
works  by  such  British  investigators  as  General  Sir  Thomas  Holdich 
in  upper  India  and  Afghanistan,  marshal  abundant  evidence  of  the 
eastern  extension  of  the  Assyrian  Empire  and  actually  of  the  settle- 
ment of  Jewish  captives  in  considerable  numbers  at  the  very  gates 
of  India.  Here  then  was  a  central  administration  dominant  from 
the  Nile  to  the  Indus  seven  centuries  earlier  than  the  period  when 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  149 

Mr.  Edmunds  seeks  to  prove  active  intercommunication.  Six  cen- 
turies before  the  same  period,  one  of  the  last  of  the  Pharaohs  opened 
a  canal  from  the  Nile  to  the  Red  Sea  to  bring  his  country  into  com- 
munication with  the  Eastern  trade  in  defiance  of  her  Mesopotamia!! 
oppressors.  Six  centuries  after  the  Christian  era  Buddhist  and 
Christian  legends  were  so  mingled  in  Western  Asia,  that  the  Koran 
absolutely  confused  the  two;  while  a  little  later  in  Eastern  Asia  a 
Chinese  emperor  issued  an  edict  forbidding  the  same  confusion  then 
prevalent  in  his  dominions. 

It  should  hardly  be  necessary  to  recall  that  Palestine  was  the 
West-land  of  the  Mesopotamian  civilization  just  as  India  was  the 
East-land ;  and  that  it  was  at  the  western  rim  of  that  ancient  culture- 
field,  and  not  from  the  Greek  or  Roman  environment,  that  the  Chris- 
tian Gospels  arose,  just  as  it  was  at  the  eastern  rim  that  the  Buddhist 
writings  were  formulated.  Without  in  any  way  assuming  identity 
of  origin  or  purpose,  it  would  be  strange  indeed  if  there  were  not 
identity  of  expression  and  parallelism  of  thought  between  these  two 
great  Canons ;  and  Mr.  Edmunds's  proof  of  that  identity  is  a  distinct 
contribution  to  human  knowledge. 

WILFRED  H.  SCHOFF. 

PHILADELPHIA,  November,  1911. 


MR.  BERTRAND  RUSSELL'S  FIRST  WORK  ON  THE 
PRINCIPLES   OF   MATHEMATICS. 

In  The  Monist  for  January,  19 10,1  Dr.  Carus  has  criticized  an 
article  of  Mr.  Bertrand  Russell's  on  "Recent  Work  on  the  Principles 
of  Mathematics,"  published  in  the  International  Monthly  for  1901. 
A  copy  of  the  article  lately  came  into  my  hands,  corrected  in  Mr. 
Russell's  handwriting  back  again  to  what  he  originally  wrote.2  The 
editor  or  type-setter  occasionally  changed  Mr.  Russell's  words  to 
words  which  he  considered  more  dignified,  perhaps.  Thus,  the 
International  Monthly  makes  Mr.  Russell  says  that  in  pure  mathe- 
matics we  "take  any  hypothesis  that  seems  assuring,  and  deduce  its 
consequences."  Mr.  Russell  had  written  "amusing,"  and  the  sub- 
stitution of  "assuring"  rather  took  away  from  the  force  of  Mr. 
Russell's  contention  that  in  mathematics  we  are  not  in  the  least  con- 

1  Vol.  XX,  pp.  46-63. 

8  Mr.  Russell  has  since  kindly  told  me  that  this  statement  is  correct. 

8  Quoted  in  The  Monist,  Vol.  XX,  p.  50. 


I5O  THE  MONIST. 

cerned  with  the  truth  or  otherwise  of  our  hypotheses  or  consequents, 
but  merely  with  the  truth  of  the  deductions. 

The  import  of  another  alteration  I  quite  fail  to  grasp.  Mr. 
Russell  wrote  that  "pure  mathematics  consists  entirely  of  assertions 
to  the  effect  that,  if  such  and  such  a  proposition  is  true  of  anything, 
then  such  and  such  another  proposition  is  true  of  that  thing."  The 
International  Monthly*  put  "asseverations"  for  "assertions" ;  and  so 
Dr.  Caruss  remarked :  "I  wish  Professor  Russell  would  not  describe 
mathematics  as  consisting  of  'asseverations' ;  the  very  idea  is  jarring 
on  my  conception  of  the  nature  of  mathematics." 

When  Dr.  Carus6  uses  here,  as  he  often  has  before,  the  word 
"anyness"  to  describe  what  is  the  fundamental  characteristic  of 
mathematics  in  his  conception,  he  seems  to  be  in  agreement  with 
one  of  the  main  tenets  of  Mr.  Russell:7  the  propositions  of  logic 
"can  be  put  into  a  form  in  which  they  apply  to  anything  whatever" ; 
"we  never  know  what  [which  thing]  we  are  talking  about"  in 
mathematics ;  the  assertions  are  that,  "if  such  and  such  a  proposition 
is  true  of  anything,  then  such  and  such  another  proposition  is  true 
of  that  thing." 

I  am  going  to  try  shortly  to  explain  Mr.  Russell  to  my  readers. 
Mr.  Russell's  work  on  the  principles  of  mathematics  and  the  rela- 
tion of  mathematics  to  logic  "is  by  no  means,"  as  Couturat  said,8 
"like  certain  philosophical  systems  in  fashion,  a  brilliant  paradox, 
an  individual  and  ephemeral  fantasy,  without  roots  in  the  past  and 
without  fruits  in  the  future,  but  the  necessary  culmination  and 
crowning  of  all  the  critical  researches  to  which  some  mathematicians 
have  given  themselves  up  for  the  last  half-century.  It  is  a  well- 
known  fact  that  modern  mathematics  have  constantly  tended  to 
deductive  rigor  of  the  reasonings  and  logical  purity  of  the  concepts. 
To  these  new  needs  of  the  scientific  spirit  a  logic  more  and  more 
exact  and  refined  had  to  respond ;  the  indispensable  instrument  of 
this  new  logic  is  the  'symbolic9  logic'  invented  by  Peano,  practised 
by  a  whole  school  of  mathematicians,  and  perfected  by  Russell. 

4  Quoted  in  The  Monist,  Vol.  XX,  p.  50. 

°  Ibid.,  p.  53. 
9  Ibid.,  p.  50. 
''Ibid.,  pp.  47,  49,  50. 

8  Les  Principes  des  mathematiques,  Paris,  1905,  pp.  v-vi.  A  translation  of 
Couturat's  work  by  the  author  of  this  article  is  in  preparation. 

"As  a  matter  of  fact,  Peano  has  always  called  his  system  "mathematical 
logic."  The  name  of  Frege  ought  to  be  mentioned  with  Peano's  in  this  con- 
nection. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

It  is  owing  to  this  logistics  (as  we  will  call,  it)  that  all  mathe- 
matical theories  have  become  susceptible  of  being  subjected  to 
a  precise  and  subtle  analysis,  and  of  being  reconstructed  logically 
with  a  small  number  of  fundamental  data  (primitive  principles  and 
notions).  It  is  owing  to  this  that  Russell  has  been  able,  while  com- 
pleting on  certain  points  this  work  of  logical  reduction,  to  system- 
atize all  the  results  acquired  in  a  vast  and  profound  synthesis,  which 
is  the  quintessence  of  preceding  works,  and  which  manifests  the 
spirit  of  modern  mathematics." 

Consider,  for  a  moment,  what  this  logical  analysis  means.  Take 
the  science  of  arithmetic.  All  its  material  and  principles  have  to 
be  reduced  to  logical  terms  and  expressed  unambiguously.  This 
enormously  important  work  is  extraordinarily  long  and  often  tedious. 
Processes  of  thought  that  most  mathematicians  perform  more  or  less 
accurately  by  "intuition"  often  take  up,  in  expression,  pages  of 
symbols  of  logical  deduction — if  such  deduction  is  possible ;  but  then 
we  get  complete,  and  not  only  "moral,"  certainty,  and  an  insight  into 
the  structure  of  certain  truths.  In  Dr.  Whitehead  and  Mr.  Russell's 
latest  book10  there  are  666  pages,  most  of  them  written  in  symbols, 
often  with  abbreviated  proofs,  and  yet  the  definition  of  numbers  is 
not  yet  reached!  Things  called  "1"  and  "2"  are  defined,  but  not 
till  the  second  volume  will  it  appear  that  they  are  numbers! 

There  is  a  story  current  in  Cambridge  that,  after  a  term's  lec- 
turing on  the  principles  of  mathematics,  Mr.  Russell  informed  his 
hearers  that  if  they  were  good  they  should  do  simple  addition  next 
term. . .  .And  so  recently  as  1888  Dedekind's  tract  of  58  pages,  Was 
sind  und  was  sollen  die  Zahlenf11  was  derided  by  some  mathema- 
ticians because  it  devoted  so  much  space  to  the  foundations  of  arith- 
metic ! 

Few  people  can  see  the  immense  importance  of  Mr.  Russell's 
work ;  fewer  know  how  laborious  it  has  been  and  by  what  splendid 
qualities  of  mind  and  character  it  has  been  inspired.  That  is  all 
I  can  say  on  this  head,  as  I  do  not  wish  to  gush  and  am  not  writing 
an  obituary  notice.  Not  quite  so  few  people  know  how  brilliant 
Mr.  Russell's  work  is.  Mr.  Russell's  investigations  have  revealed 
some  very  striking  things,  and  Mr.  Russell  has  said  them  strikingly 
— said  them,  too,  in  books  and  articles  which  are  read  with  delight, 
and  sometimes  with  profit,  by  those  who  are  untrained  to  follow 

10  Principia  Mathematica,  Vol.  I,  Cambridge,  1910. 

"English  translation  by  W.  W.  Beman,  in  Dedekind's  Essays  on  the 
Theory  of  Numbers,  Chicago,  1901. 


152  THE  MONIST. 

Mr.  Russell's  work.  I  suppose  Mr.  Russell  has  a  natural  love  of 
paradox,  but  his  paradox  is  always  used  to  give  point  to  the  state- 
ment of  some  truth.  In  his  talk  and  writings,  Mr.  Russell  is  con- 
scientious, truth-loving,  keen  and  witty. 

I  now  propose  to  analyze  the  International  Monthly  article  and 
to  try  to  show  how  the  fundamental  doctrines  of  the  Principles  of 
Mathematics  are  shortly  stated  in  it.  This  will  continue  my  article 
in  The  Monist  for  January,  1910  ;12  and  in  future  I  hope  to  trace 
Mr.  Russell's  work  beyond  1903. 


The  first  published  indication  of  the  effect  of  Peano's  work 
on  Russell  appeared  in  an  article  by  Russell  on  "Recent  Work  on 
the  Principles  of  Mathematics"  in  the  International  Monthly  for 
1901. 13  Boole,  he  said,1*  was  "mistaken  in  supposing  that  he  was 
dealing  with  the  laws  of  thought:  the  question  how  people  actually 
think  was  quite  irrelevant  to  him, ....  His  book  was  in  fact  con- 
cerned with  formal  logic,  and  this  is  the  same  thing  as  mathematics." 
Then  came1*  a  definition  of  pure  mathematics:  "Pure  mathematics 
consists  entirely  of  assertions  to  the  effect  that  if  such  and  such  a 
proposition  is  true  of  anything,  then  such  and  such  a  proposition 
is  true  of  that  thing.  It  is  essential  not  to  discuss  whether  the  first 
proposition  is  really  true,  and  not  to  mention  what  the  anything  is  of 
which  it  is  supposed  to  be  true.  Both  these  points  would  belong 
to  applied  mathematics.  We  start,  in  pure  mathematics,  from 
certain  rules  of  inference,  by  which  we  can  infer  that  */  one  propo- 
sition is  true,  then  so  is  some  other  proposition.  These  rules  of  in- 
ference constitute  the  principles  of  formal  logic.  We  then  take  any 
hypothesis  that  seems  amusing,  and  deduce  its  consequences.  // 
our  hypothesis  is  about  anything,  and  not  about  some  one  or  more 
particular  things,  then  our  deductions  constitute  mathematics.  Thus 
mathematics  may  be  defined  as  the  subject  in  which  we  never  know 
what  we  are  talking  about,  nor  whether  what  we  are  saying  is  true." 

The  reduction  of  mathematics  to  logic  was  spoken  of:16  "Now 
the  fact  is  that,  though  there  are  indefinables  and  indemonstrables 
in  every  branch  of  applied  mathematics,  there  are  none  in  pure 

12  Vol.  XX,  pp.  93-"8. 
"Vol.  IV,  pp.  83-101. 
ulbid.f  p.  83. 

15  Ibid.,  pp.  83-84.    For  "assertions"  was  misprinted  "asseverations,"  and 
for  "amusing"  was  misprinted  "assuring." 
19  Ibid.,  p.  84. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  153 

mathematics  except  such  as  belong  to  general  logic.  Logic,  broadly 
speaking,  is  distinguished  by  the  fact  that  its  propositions  can  be 
put  into  a  form  in  which  they  apply  to  anything  whatever.  All  pure 
mathematics — arithmetic,  analysis,  and  geometry — is  built  up  by 
combinations  of  the  primitive  ideas  of  logic,  and  its  propositions  are 
deduced  from  the  general  axioms  of  logic,  such  as  the  syllogism 
and  the  other  rules  of  inference." 

When  dealing  with  questions  of  the  principles  of  mathematics, 
the  function  of  symbolism  is  exactly  the  opposite  to  that  of  sym- 
bolism in  the  other  parts  of  mathematics.  Russell  said:1?  "The  fact 
is  that  symbolism  is  useful  because  it  makes  things  difficult.  (This 
is  not  true  of  the  advanced  parts  of  mathematics,  but  only  of  the 
beginnings.)  What  we  wish  to  know  is,  what  can  be  deduced  from 
what.  Now,  in  the  beginnings,  everything  is  self-evident;  and  it 
is  very  hard  to  see  whether  one  self-evident  proposition  follows 
from  another  or  not.  Obviousness  is  always  the  enemy  of  correct- 
ness. Hence  we  invent  some  new  and  difficult  symbolism,  in  which 
nothing  seems  obvious.  Then  we  set  up  certain  rules  for  operating 
on  the  symbols,  and  the  whole  thing  becomes  mechanical.  In  this 
way  we  find  out  what  must  be  taken  as  premise  and  what  can  be 
demonstrated  or  defined." 

ii. 

Referring  to  Peano's  three  indefinables  in  arithmetic,  Russell 
remarked:18  "Even  these  three  can  be  explained  by  means  of  the 
notions  of  relation  and  class ;  but  this  requires  the  logic  of  relations 
which  Professor  Peano  has  never  taken  up." 

Russell19  then  indicated  his  contradiction: 

"There  is  a  greatest  of  all  infinite  [cardinal]  numbers,  which 
is  the  number  of  all  things  altogether,  of  every  sort  and  kind.  It 
is  obvious  that  there  cannot  be  a  greater  number  than  this,  because, 
if  everything  has  been  taken,  there  is  nothing  left  to  add.  Cantor 
has  a  proof  that  there  is  no  greater  number,  and  if  this  proof  were 
valid,  the  contradictions  of  infinity  would  re-appear  in  a  sublimated 
form.  But  on  this  one  point,  the  master  has  been  guilty  of  a  very 

subtle  fallacy,  which  I  hope  to  explain  in  some  future  work." 

*       *       * 

Russell's  statement  of  Zeno's  puzzle  about  Achilles  and  the 
tortoise  was:20 

17  Ibid.,  pp.  85-86.  18  Ibid.,  p.  87.  10  Ibid.,  p.  95- 

30  Ibid.,  pp.  95-96. 


154  THE  MONIST. 

"The  argument  is  this:  Let  Achilles  and  the  tortoise  start 
along  a  road  at  the  same  time,  the  tortoise  (as  is  only  fair)  being 
allowed  a  handicap.  Let  Achilles  go  twice  as  fast  as  the  tortoise, 
or  ten  times  or  a  hundred  times  as  fast.  Then  he  will  never  reach 
the  tortoise.  For  at  every  moment  the  tortoise  is  somewhere,  and 
Achilles  is  somewhere;  and  neither  is  ever  twice  in  the  same  place 
while  the  race  is  going  on.  Thus  the  tortoise  goes  to  just  as  many 
places  as  Achilles  does,  because  each  is  in  one  place  at  one  moment, 
and  in  another  at  any  other  moment.  But  if  Achilles  were  to  catch 
up  with  the  tortoise  the  places  where  the  tortoise  would  have  been 
would  be  only  part  of  the  places  where  Achilles  would  have  been. 
Here,  we  must  suppose,  Zeno  appealed  to  the  maxim  that  the  whole 
has  more  terms  than  the  part.  Thus,  if  Achilles  were  to  overtake  the 
tortoise,  he  would  have  been  in  more  places  than  the  tortoise;  but 
we  saw  that  he  must,  in  any  period,  be  in  exactly  as  many  places 
as  the  tortoise.  Hence  we  infer  that  he  can  never  catch  the  tortoise. 
This  argument  is  strictly  correct  if  we  allow  the  axiom  that  the 
whole  has  more  terms  than  the  part.  As  the  conclusion  is  absurd, 
the  axiom  must  be  rejected,  and  then  all  goes  well.  But  there  is 
no  good  word  to  be  said  for  the  philosophers  of  the  past  two  thou- 
sand years  and  more,  who  have  all  allowed  the  axiom  and  denied 

the  conclusion." 

*      *      * 

The  converse  of  the  Achilles,  which  Russell  called  "the  paradox 
of  Tristram  Shandy,"  was  then  described  ;21  and  the  remark  was 
made22that  the  notion  of  continuity  depends  upon  that  of  order,  and 
that  "nowadays,  quantity  is  banished  altogether  [from  mathematics] 
except  from  one  little  corner  of  geometry,  while  order  more  and 
more  reigns  supreme."  Nowadays,  too,  a  limit  is  defined  ordinally.23 

Then  :2«  "Geometry,  like  arithmetic,  has  been  subsumed  in  recent 
times  under  the  general  study  of  order.  It  was  formerly  supposed 
that  geometry  was  the  study  of  the  nature  of  the  space  in  which  we 
live,  and  accordingly  it  was  urged  by  those  who  held  that  what  exists 
can  only  be  known  empirically,  that  geometry  should  really  be 
regarded  as  belonging  to  applied  mathematics.  But  it  has  grad- 
ually appeared,  by  the  increase  of  non-Euclidean  systems,  that  ge- 
ometry throws  no  more  light  upon  the  nature  of  space  than  arithmetic 

n  Ibid.,  pp.  96-97- 
"Ibid.,  p.  97. 
*Ibid.,  pp.  97-98. 
"Ibid.,  p.  98. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  155 

throws  upon  the  population  of  the  United  States.  Geometry  is  a 
whole  collection  of  deductive  sciences  based  on  a  corresponding  col- 
lection of  sets  of  axioms.  One  set  of  axioms  is  Euclid's;  other 
equally  good  sets  of  axioms  lead  to  other  results.  Whether  Euclid's 
axioms  are  true,  is  a  question  as  to  which  the  pure  mathematician 
is  indifferent ;  and  what  is  more,  it  is  a  question  which  it  is  theoret- 
ically impossible  to  answer  with  certainty  in  the  affirmative.  It 
might  possibly  be  shown,  by  very  careful  measurements,  that  Euclid's 
axioms  are  false ;  but  no  measurements  could  ever  assure  us  (owing 
to  the  errors  of  observation)  that  they  are  exactly  true.  Thus  the 
geometer  leaves  to  the  man  of  science  to  decide,  as  best  he  may, 
what  axioms  are  most  nearly  true  in  the  actual  world.  The  geometer 
takes  any  set  of  axioms  that  seem  interesting,  and  deduces  their  con- 
sequences. What  defines  geometry,  in  this  sense,  is  that  the  axioms 
must  give  rise  to  a  series  of  more  than  one  dimension.  And  it  is  thus 
that  geometry  becomes  a  department  in  the  study  of  order." 

Russell25  then  shortly  dealt  with  the  methods  used  by  Peano 
and  Fano  in  geometry,  and  finally26  remarked  that  "the  proof  that 
all  pure  mathematics,  including  geometry,  is  nothing  but  formal 
logic,  is  a  fatal  blow  to  the  Kantian  philosophy." 

in. 

Let  us  now  point  out  how  this  popular  article  gives  indications 
of  his  logical  work  up  to  1903. 

To  begin  with,  the  two  great  influences  on  Russell's  mathemat- 
ical and  logical  work  were  Georg  Cantor  and  Peano.  Cantor  had, 
in  1895  and  1897,27  brought  his  researches  on  transfinite  numbers 
and  ordinal  types  to  a  close  by  two  articles  in  which  the  principles  of 
the  subject  were  stated  in  an  almost  perfect  logical  form.  Obviously, 
the  whole  question  threw  a  great  and  welcome  light  on  the  prin- 
ciples of  arithmetic.28  Peano  invented  a  symbolic  logic  which  was 
especially  adapted  to  the  analysis  and  expression  of  mathematical 
theories.  But  Peano's  logic  was  incomplete.  It  neglected  the  logic 
of  relations,  which  was  founded  and  developed  by  De  Morgan, 
C.  S.  Peirce,  and  Schroder;  and  only  contained  a  symbolical  ex- 
pression of  the  theory — unused,  by  the  way,  in  Peano's  symbolic 

xlbid.f  pp.  99-100. 

M  Ibid.,  p.  101. 

*  Mathematische  Annalen,  Vols.  XLVT  and  XLIX.  An  annotated  trans- 
lation of  these  articles  by  the  author  is  in  preparation. 

88  Cf.  my  article  on  "Transfinite  Numbers  and  the  Principles  of  Mathe- 
matics" in  The  Monist  for  January,  1910. 


156  THE  MONIST. 

exposition  of  arithmetic — of  the  "representations"  of  Richard  Dede- 
kind.29  The  logic  of  relations  was,  as  Schroder  had  observed,  neces- 
sary for  the  translation  of  Cantor's  conceptions  and  proofs  into  a 
symbolic  (speaking  technically)  form;  and  it  was  necessary  in  order 
to  complete  Peano's  theory  of  arithmetic  by  denning  in  logical 
terms  the  three  indefinables  referred  to  above.  Russell  completed 
Peano's  logic  by  a  logic  of  relations  in  which  the  Peirce- Schroder 
ideas  were  modified  so  as  to  fit  in  with  a  logic  which  comprised 
more  subtle  distinctions  than  that  of  Schroder,  in  two  papers,  "Sur 
la  logique  des  relations,  avec  des  applications  a  la  theorie  des  series," 
and  "Theorie  des  series  bien-ordonnees,"  which  were  published  in 
Peano's  Revue  de  Mathematiques  for  1902,3°  and  of  the  first  of 
which  an  account  was  given  in  Russell's  Principles  of  Mathematics 
of  1903.3 l  The  logic  of  relations  gave  to  Russell  the  means  of 
defining  Peano's  indefinables  of  arithmetic,  and  of  proving  his  primi- 
tive propositions  of  arithmetic.32 

Peano  had  emphasized  that  it  was  the  notion  of  implication 
between  propositions  containing  variables — or,  as  Russell  expressed 
it,  of  formal  implications33  between  prepositional  functions?*  and 
not  implication  between  (constant)  propositions,  that  is  used  in 
mathematics.  Further,  the  development  of  non-Euclidean  geom- 
etry had  shown  in  the  most  striking  manner  that,  in  pure  mathe- 
matics, as  in  formal  logic,  we  are  not  concerned  with  the  truth  or 
otherwise  of  the  hypotheses.  "Until  the  nineteenth  century,"  said 
Russell,35  "geometry  meant  Euclidean  geometry,  i.  e.,  a  certain 
system  of  propositions  deduced  from  premises  supposed  to  describe 
the  space  in  which  we  live.  . .  .,"  but  now,  owing  to  investigations 
with  premises  other  than  Euclid's,  "geometry  has  become. . .  .a  sub- 
ject in  which  the  assertions  are  that  such  and  such  consequences 
follow  from  such  and  such  premises,  not  that  entities  such  as  the 
premises  describe  actually  exist."  And  all  this  goes  some  way 

29  Cf.  the  English  translation  of  Dedekind's  pamphlet  in  Dedekind's  Essays 
on  the  Theory  of  Numbers,  Chicago,  1901. 

80  An  account  of  Peano's  and  Russell's  logic  was  given  by  A.  N.  White- 
head  in  his  paper  "On  Cardinal  Numbers"  in  the  Amer.  Journal  of  Math., 
Vol.  XXIV,  1902,  pp.  367-394- 

31  The  Principles  of  Mathematics,  Vol.  I  [the  Principia  Mathematica  of 
Whitehead  and  Russell,  of  which  the  first  volume  was  published  in  1910,  takes 
the  place  of  the  second  volume],  pp.  23-26;  cf.  Couturat,  op.  cit.,  pp.  27-34. 

38  Principles,  pp.  124-128. 

83  Ibid.,  pp.  5,  n,  14,  36-41;  Couturat,  op.  cit.,  pp.  4,  21. 
**  Principles,  pp.  13,  19;  Couturat,  op.  cit.,  p.  17. 
88  Principles,  pp.  372-373- 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  157 

towards  explaining  the  definition  of  pure  mathematics  with  which 
Russell's  book  begins: 

"Pure  mathematics  is  the  class  of  all  propositions  of  the  form 
(p  implies  q,'  where  p  and  q  are  propositions  containing  one  or  more 
variables,  the  same  in  the  two  propositions,  and  neither  p  nor  q 
contains  any  constants  except  logical  constants.  And  logical  con- 
stants are  all  notions  definable  in  terms  of  the  following:  Implica- 
tion, the  relation  of  a  term  to  a  class  of  which  it  is  a  member,  the 
notion  of  such  that,  the  notion  of  relation,  and  such  further  notions 
as  may  be  involved  in  the  general  notion  of  propositions  of  the 
above  form.  In  addition  to  these,  mathematics  uses  a  notion  which 
is  not  a  constituent  of  the  propositions  which  it  considers,  namely 
the  notion  of  truth." 

In  this  definition  culminates  the  discovery  contributed  to  by 
Leibniz,  Frege,  Dedekind,  Schroder,  and  a  host  of  others,  that  pure 
mathematics  is  logic  and  logic  alone.  Hence  Russell's36  anti-Kant- 
ianism. 

*  *       * 

In  the  question  of  infinity,  we  have  a  discussion  of  Zeno's 
puzzles,37and  meet  again  the  paradox  of  Tristram  Shandy.38  When 
discussing  continuity,  Russell39made  more  explicit  Cantor's  dis- 
covery (1895)  that  it  is  a  purely  ordinal  notion;  and  then,  too, 
Russell  succeeded  in  maintaining  his  theses  that  the  theory  of  limits 
is  purely  ordinal,*0  that  geometry  is  the  study  of  order,*1  and  that 
the  notion  of  quantity  is  superfluous  in  mathematics.*2 

*  *       * 

Finally  we  come  to  Russell's*3  contradiction.  Starting  from  a 
study  of  Cantor's  proof  of  1892  that  there  is  no  greatest  cardinal 
number,  Russell  discovered  a  very  simple  argument:  If  w  denotes 
the  class  of  all  those  entities  x  such  that  x  is  not  a  member  of  x ; 
then,  obviously,  if  w  is  a  member  of  w,  w  is  not  a  member  of  w, 
while  if  w  is  not  a  member  of  w,  w  is  a  member  of  w.  This  contra- 

86  Principles,  pp.  4,  158,  259,  373,  442,  456-461;  Couturat,  op.  cit.,  pp.  235- 
308. 

87  Principles,  pp.  347-353,  358-360. 
"Ibid.,  pp.  358-360. 

89  Ibid.,  pp.  296-303 ;  Couturat,  op.  cit.,  pp.  91-97. 

40  Principles,  pp.  276-277. 

41  Ibid.,  p.  372 ;  Couturat,  op.  cit.,  p.  134. 

a  Principles,  p.  158;  Couturat,  op.  cit.,  p.  98. 
48  Principles,  pp.  364-368,  101-107. 


158  THE  MONIST. 

diction,  which  threw  doubt  upon  the  legitimacy  of  the  concept  of  class, 
and  hence  upon  that  of  the  science  of  arithmetic,  showed  itself  as 
allied  in  principle  to  the  paradoxes  in  the  theory  of  aggregates  dis- 
covered by  Burali-Forti,  Konig,  Richard,  and  others,  and  to  the 
old  logical  difficulty  about  the  Cretan  who  said  that  Cretans  were 
liars,  and  was  only  satisfactorily  solved  by  Russell  in  1905.  Of 
this  more  elsewhere. 

It  only  remains  at  present  to  refer  to  the  work  of  Frege.  He 
did  his  magnificent  work  on  the  principles  of  logic  and  mathematics 
alone  and  almost  too  independently,  and  his  subtle  distinctions  and 
acute  analysis  have  had  great  influence  on  modern  work.  But  at 
first  Russell  had  hardly  heard  of  him,  and  re-discovered  for  himself 
many  of  his  distinctions  and  views.  In  his  Principles,44  Russell  de- 
voted many  pages  to  a  careful  critical  estimate  of  Frege's  work. 
I  hope  to  give  an  account  of  Frege's  work  later. 

PHILIP  E.  B.  JOURDAIN. 

THE  LODGE,  GIRTON,  CAMBRIDGE,  ENGLAND. 


ALFRED  BINET.* 

OBITUARY. 

Readers  of  The  Monist  are  well  acquainted  with  the  name  of 
Alfred  Binet.  That  eminent  psychologist  died  at  Paris  October  18, 
1911,  at  the  age  of  54,  from  an  attack  of  cerebral  apoplexy.  He  was 
born  at  Nice,  July  11,  1857.  He  first  took  up  the  study  of  law, 
but  later  turned  his  attention  to  natural  sciences,  and  finally  directed 
all  his  efforts  to  psychology.  In  1894  in  collaboration  with  Beaunis 
at  the  laboratory  of  physiological  psychology  of  the  Sorbonne, 
he  founded  the  Annee  psychologiqne,  an  important  publication  of 
permanent  value. 

His  principle  works  are  Vie  psychique  des  micro-organismes 
(English  edition,  The  Psychic  Life  of  Micro-Organisms,  Open 
Court  Publishing  Co.,  1894)  ;  Psychologic  du  raisonnement  (English 
edition,  The  Psychology  of  Reasoning,  Open  Court  Publishing  Co., 
1899) ;  Le  magnetisme  animal,  Les  alterations  de  la  personnalite, 
Psychologic  des  grands  calculateurs  et  joueurs  d'echechs,  Etude  ex- 
perimentale  de  ^intelligence,  L'ame  et  le  corps.  To  these  we  should 
also  add  a  number  of  articles  on  an  equal  variety  of  subjects,  capil- 

44  Pp.  501-522. 

*  Translated  for  The  Monist. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

lary   circulation,   the   pulse,   emotions,   character,   graphology,   the 
mystery  of  painting,  etc. 

In  his  last  years  he  was  particularly  interested  in  the  "psycho- 
logical study  of  the  child"  and  for  this  purpose  founded  a  society 
which  bore  this  title.  In  collaboration  with  Dr.  Simon  he  published 
a  number  of  studies  on  abnormal  children.  Very  recently  he  sug- 
gested a  system  of  "measurement  of  the  development  of  intelligence 
in  children"  which  seemed  very  simple  and  practical  and  has  been 
tested  by  educators  in  many  countries. 

Simply  to  read  the  list  of  books  and  articles  published  by  Binet 
might  give  the  impression  of  too  great  a  dispersion  of  forces.  It 
is  further  true  that  the  work  of  Binet  does  not,  like  that  of  other 
psychologists,  present  the  development  of  one  dominant  thought  pur- 
sued through  all  the  problems  of  psychology.  Nevertheless  his  work 
shows  a  unity  of  quite  another  kind,  a  unity  of  method.  Binet 
always  endeavored  to  apply  the  processes  of  experimentation  or  di- 
rect observation  to  the  most  diverse  questions,  and  consequently  we 
may  say  that  inasmuch  as  his  works  tended  towards  the  control  or 
invention  of  facts,  they  form  an  important  whole  and  bear  constant 
witness  to  a  truly  scientific  spirit.  Although  he  did  not  conceive 
any  broad  hypotheses  and  did  not  aim  at  extended  or  conclusive 
solutions  he  was  a  prudent  investigator  of  broad  culture,  rich  and 
versatile  intelligence  and  an  excellent  worker. 

LUCIEN  ARREAT. 

PARIS,  FRANCE. 


MAGIC  SQUARES  BY  REVERSION. 

The  present  number  of  The  Monist  contains  an  article  on  magic 
squares  by  Dr.  C.  Planck  entitled  "The  Method  of  Reversion."  This 
reminds  the  Editor  of  his  own  contributions  to  the  problem  of  the 
construction  of  magic  squares  which  appeared  in  Mr.  W.  S.  An- 
drews's  book  on  Magic  Squares  and  Cubes  under  the  title,  "Reflec- 
tions on  Magic  Squares." 

Since  these  reflections  were  written  I  have  come  to  the  conclu- 
sion that  a  popular  name  for  the  several  arrangements  of  the  num- 
bers in  their  cells  would  help  greatly  to  make  the  idea  clearer.  On 
page  115  I  have  called  the  ordinary  order  o,  the  reversed  ordinary 
ro,  the  inverse  of  the  ordinary  arrangement  if  and  by  ri  is  understood 
the  reversed  inverted  order.  Considering  the  fact  that  all  these 


l6O  THE  MONIST. 

arrangements  are  brought  about  by  a  system  of  inversion  which 
corresponds  closely  to  reading  the  figures  off  in  mirror  writing,  we 
may  consider  them  as  originated  by  placing  a  mirror  on  two  sides 
of  the  original  square.  If  o  is  flanked  by  a  mirror  from  the  top 
to  the  bottom  it  produces  the  order  i.  If  the  mirror  is  placed  at  the 
bottom  it  produces  the  order  n  which  mirrors  the  picture  as  if  re- 
flected in  the  surface  of  a  lake,  while  the  order  ro  lies  in  the  corner 
between  the  two  mirrors,  being  the  reflection  of  either  mirror  in 
the  other  and  this  double  inversion  which  we  have  called  ro  cor- 
responds directly  with  the  picture  which  appears  on  the  ground 
glass  of  a  photographer's  camera.  Accordingly  the  several  orders 
on  a  plane  surface  might  popularly  be  called  the  "original,"  the 
"mirror"  reflection,  the  "lake"  reflection  and  the  "ground  glass"  pic- 
ture. 

original     mirror 

jd  LL 

771  F 

lake     ground  glass 
FOUR  WAYS  OF  INVERSION  IN  A  PLANE. 

Of  course  the  conditions  of  such  reflections  grow  more  com- 
plicated if  we  venture  from  the  plane  into  tridimensional  space,  and 
it  can  be  extended  into  4-  and  w-dimensional  spaces.  It  appears  to 
me  that  this  idea  of  inversion  rests  ultimately  on  the  same  basis  as 
Dr.  Planck's  method  of  reversions.  p.  c. 


IM 
VOL.  XXII.  APRIL,  1912.  NO.  2 

THE  MONIST 


CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  CHRISTIANITY  TO  BUD- 
DHISM.1 

THE  Buddhist  religion  had  penetrated  to  the  most  ex- 
treme northwestern  part  of  India  about  the  middle  of 
the  third  century  B.  C.  There  it  developed  in  the  direction 
which  expressed  itself  most  distinctively  in  the  deification 
of  the  person  of  Buddha  and  in  the  transformation  of  the 
Nirvana-concept  into  the  idea  of  a  beatified  continuous 
existence ;  there  too  arose  the  most  essential  points  which 
distinguish  northern  Buddhism  from  southern  in  doctrine 
and  forms  of  worship.  This  development  found  a  positive 
conclusion  in  the  establishment  of  a  new  school  which 
assumed  the  name  Mahayana,  "The  Great  Vehicle/'  and 
which  flourished  in  that  region  until  about  the  eighth  cen- 
tury A.  D.  After  the  founding  of  that  school  the  older 
original  Buddhism  in  contrast  to  it  was  called  Hinayana, 
"The  Small  Vehicle." 

Expositions  of  Buddhism  usually  treat  the  Mahayana 
disparagingly,  first  because  it  places  value  upon  the  ex- 
ternalities of  worship,  and  in  the  second  place  because  in 
its  philosophical  speculation  it  evinces  the  strongest  skepti- 
cism in  teaching  that  Nothing  is  the  true  essence  of  things. 
But  more  important  than  these  aspects  of  the  varied  con- 
tents of  the  Mahayana  is  the  new  ideal  of  life  with  which 
it  has  replaced  the  benevolent  but  fundamentally  egoistic 
indifference — freedom  not  only  from  passions  but  even 
from  all  human  emotions.  This  new  ideal,  which  the  early 

1  Authorized  translation  from  the  German  by  Lydia  G.  Robinson. 


l62  THE  MONIST. 

Buddhist  type  of  saint  no  longer  satisfied,  was  that  of 
loving  devotion  and  active  compassion.  H.  Kern2  says 
truly :  "It  is  by  that  feeling  of  fervent  devotion,  combined 
with  the  preaching  of  active  compassion,  that  the  creed 
has  enlisted  the  sympathy  of  numerous  millions  of  people 
and  has  become  a  factor  in  the  history  of  mankind  of  much 
greater  importance  than  orthodox  Buddhism."  Southern 
Buddhism,  which  remained  true  to  the  ancient  ideal,  pos- 
sessed no  such  winning  power. 

Moreover,  the  Mahayana  exhibits  ideas  pleasing  to  the 
heart  and  imagination  which  run  directly  counter  to  the 
doctrines  of  the  Hinayana.  The  old  Buddhism  acknowledges 
no  soul  persisting  throughout  the  course  of  life  and  knows 
no  God,  for  the  national  gods  which  it  recognizes  are 
transient  beings  held  captive  in  Samsara.  In  the  Maha- 
yana we  find  a  belief  both  in  a  personal  soul  and  in  God, 
at  least  in  a  kind  of  God.  In  a  paradise  called  Sukhavati 
where  a  reflection  of  the  earthly  Buddha,  Amitabha,  "the 
one  surrounded  by  immeasurable  light,"  sits  enthroned 
in  godlike  fashion,  the  souls  of  the  pious  are  born  again 
after  death  in  the  buds  of  lotus  flowers  gradually  to  grow 
in  the  blossoms  according  to  their  deserts ;  and  resting  upon 
the  lotus  leaves  they  hear  the  good  law  preached  to  them 
by  Amitabha  or  sung  by  birds  in  the  leafy  trees.3 

According  to  the  traditional  statement,  repeated  even 
by  Pischel  and  Edv.  Lehmann,4  the  Mahayana  was  founded 
by  Nagarjuna,  whose  activity  we  would  place  rather  in  the 
middle  than  in  the  second  half  of  the  second  century  after 
Christ.  But  this  statement  is  not  correct.  Nagarjuna,  who 
as  originator  of  the  Madhyamika  sect  introduced  into  Bud- 

2Manual  of  Indian  Buddhism  (Grundriss  der  Indo-arischen  Philologie  und 
Altertumskunde,  III,  8,  Strassburg,  1896),  p.  124. 

3Teitaro  Suzuki,  Outlines  of  Mahayana  Buddhism,  London,  1907;  H. 
Hackmann,  Buddhism  as  a  Religion,  London,  1910,  pp.  50  ff. ;  Max  Miiller, 
Last  Essays,  II,  pp.  304,  305. 

*  Pischel,  Leben  und  Lehre  des  Buddha.  Leipsic,  1906,  p.  108;  2d  ed.  by 
Liiders,  p.  104.  Lehmann,  Der  Buddhismus,  p.  227. 


CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  CHRISTIANITY  TO  BUDDHISM.     163 

dhism  the  doctrine  of  Nothing  as  the  only  reality,  was  in- 
deed one  of  the  most  significant  and  influential  exponents  of 
the  Mahayana5  and  presumably  the  organizer  of  that 
school;  but  its  foundation,  that  is  to  say  the  first  literary 
exposition  of  its  doctrines,  must  be  placed  about  sixty  to 
seventy  years  earlier.  This  was  the  work  of  a  man  who 
has  latterly  engaged  the  attention  of  the  most  distinguished 
Indologues,  namely  the  famous  and  versatile  monk  Ashva- 
ghosha,  an  elder  contemporary  of  King  Kanishka,  hence 
in  all  probability  living  in  the  second  half  of  the  first  cen- 
tury after  Christ.6  Ashvaghosha  was  an  old  man  at  the 
time  of  the  birth  of  Nagarjuna,  that  is  to  say,  when  the 
last  Buddhist  council  was  held  at  Jalandhara  under  King 
Kanishka  about  100  A.  D.,  if  we  may  take  as  a  basis  of 
calculation  the  most  probable  but  not  quite  assured  dating 
of  King  Kanishka  (last  quarter  of  the  first  and  the  be- 
ginning of  the  second  century).  Cunningham,  Pischel, 
the  sinologue  O.  Franke,  Fleet,  and  Liiders  place  Kanishka 
in  the  first  century  before  Christ. 

Therefore  the  appearance  and  the  first  propagation  of 
the  ideas  of  the  Mahayana  fall  in  the  last  decades  before 
the  council  at  Jalandhara. 

It  has  occurred  to  many  that  Christian  influences  may 
have  had  some  effect  in  the  transformation  of  the  Buddhist 
religion  into  the  Mahayana  form.  Thus  the  sinologue 
Samuel  Beal7  found  "in  Ashvaghosha's  writings  many 

5H.  Kern,  Manual,  6,  pp.  122,  127.  Teitaro  Suzuki,  Agvaghosha's  Dis- 
course on  the  Awakening  of  Faith  in  the  Mahayana',  translated  for  the  first 
time  from  the  Chinese  version.  Chicago,  1900,  p.  43. 

6  Besides  his  best  known  work,  the   Buddhacharita  which   is  a  poetical 
biography    of    Buddha,    Ashvaghosha    wrote    a    collection    of    didactic    tales 
(Sutralarnkara)   and  theological  works  and  was  also  a  successful  composer 
and  musician.     Lately  too  by  a  happy  discovery  of  Heinrich  Luders  he  has 
been  shown  to  be  a  dramatist  (Sitzungsberichte  der  K.  Preussischen  Akademie 
der  Wissenschaften,  phil.  hist  Klasse,  1911,  pp.  388  ff.,  especially  399;  cf.  also 
M.  Anesaki,  Encyclopaedia  of  Religion  and  Ethics,  II,  pp.  159,  160;  S.  Levi, 
"Agvaghosha,  le  Sutralarnkara  et  ses  sources,"  Journ.  As.  S.,  Series  X,  Vol. 
XII,  pp.  57  ff- 

7  Abstract  of  Four  Lectures  on  Buddhist  Literature  in  China.  London,  1882, 
P-  95- 


164  THE  MONIST. 

allusions  and  illustrations  derived  apparently  from  foreign, 
and  perhaps  Christian,  sources/'  and  arrived  at  the  view 
"that  much  in  the  Buddhist  development  coming  under 
the  name  of  the  Greater  Vehicle  may  be  explained  on  this 
ground."  In  another  passage8  he  speaks  in  a  more  de- 
cided tone  of  the  intercommunication  in  those  days  between 
East  and  West  that  "shaped  the  later  school  of  Buddhism 
into  a  pseudo-Christian  form." 

A  similar  judgment  has  latterly  been  the  fate  of  the 
oldest  text-book  of  the  Mahayana,  Ashvaghosha's  Dis- 
course on  the  Awakening  of  Faith  in  the  Mahayana,  which 
is  not  preserved  in  the  Sanskrit  original  but  only  in  two 
Chinese  translations.9  The  missionary  Dr.  Timothy  Rich- 
ard, who  has  translated  this  work  into  English  (  Shanghai, 
1907),  finds  in  it  Christian  ideas  and  influences  and  there- 
fore reproduces  the  Buddhist  terminology  very  freely  in 
an  entirely  Christian  mode  of  expression,10  whereas  on  the 
other  hand  an  earlier  and  more  exact  translator,  the  Japa- 
nese Teitaro  Suzuki,  a  Buddhist  (see  above  Note  4)  has 
discovered  no  Christian  traces  of  any  kind  in  the  book. 

Lately,  too,  Christian  influence  in  the  Mahayana  has 
been  maintained  by  the  Jesuit  Joseph  Dahlmann11  with 
great  determination  and  with  an  attempt  at  detailed  scien- 
tific proofs.  In  what  follows  I  shall  first  have  to  take  his 
expositions  into  critical  account. 

In  chapters  25-27  relating  to  the  art  of  Gandhara,  that 
is  of  the  Kabul  valley  and  the  surrounding  country,  Dahl- 
mann has  undertaken  to  show  that  these  monuments  of 
Buddhist  art  which  reflect  the  Mahayana  thought-cycle 
betray  not  only  the  generally  recognized  Greco-Roman 

8  Op.  dt.  Introduction,  p.  xiv. 

"Bunyiu  Nanjio,  Catalogue  of  the  Chinese  Translation  of  the  Buddhist 
Tripitaka.  Oxford,  1883,  No.  1249,  1250.  There  the  title  of  the  Sanskrit 
original  is  given  as  Mahayana-shraddhotpada[na]-shastra. 

10  The  Open  Court,  XXV,  1911,  pp.  251  ff 

11  Indische  Fahrten  (2  vols.,  Freiburg,  1908)  II,  pp.  100  ff. 


CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  CHRISTIANITY  TO  BUDDHISM.     165 

influence  but  also  a  profound  Christian  influence.  From 
the  middle  of  the  first  century  of  the  Christian  era  "that 
change  in  worship  and  art  began  to  be  consummated  in 
Gandhara.  The  same  Buddha  whose  figure  had  been  pains- 
takingly avoided  appears  all  at  once  in  the  monuments  of 
Buddhist  art,  and  not  indeed  as  the  simple  herald  of  salva- 
tion as  in  ancient  Buddhistic  legend,  but  as  in  the  message 
of  salvation  of  the  Gospels,  as  God  and  as  Saviour  of  the 
world.  He  appears  as  God  and  Saviour  not  in  Indian  gar- 
ments but  in  a  garb  such  as  was  worn  by  the  higher  classes 
in  Antioch  and  Alexandria,  in  Jerusalem  and  Rome  during 
the  first  centuries  of  the  Roman  empire."12 

True  and  noteworthy,  to  be  sure,  is  the  circumstance 
that  the  likeness  of  Buddha  appears  first  of  all  in  the  art 
of  Gandhara.  Most  investigators  in  Indian  archeology 
have  sought  the  reason  for  this  strange  fact  and  have 
found  it  in  part  (as  in  the  case  of  Fergusson  and  Cunning- 
ham) in  the  assumption  that  the  Buddhists  had  learned 
idolatry  from  the  Greeks,  whereas  Griinwedel  would  fain 
explain  the  rise  of  the  Buddha  image  from  the  natural 
development  of  Buddhism.  In  early  Buddhist  art  as  rep- 
resented in  the  monuments  of  Sanchi,  Bharhut  and  Bud- 
dhagaya  in  Central  India,  the  original  home  of  Buddhism, 
since  the  middle  of  the  third  century  B.  C.,  any  likeness 
of  Buddha  is  entirely  absent.  Where  a  likeness  of  Bud- 
dha would  naturally  be  expected  in  the  representations 
of  his  life  and  works  we  regularly  find  instead,  in  strange 
contrast  to  the  lifelike  pictures  of  all  other  participants  in 
the  scene,  a  symbol  such  as  the  tree  of  knowledge,  a  reli- 
quary, or  the  wheel  of  the  law.  In  the  art  of  Gandhara, 
on  the  other  hand,  the  likeness  of  Buddha  is  the  central 
figure.  Here  it  appears  everywhere  in  a  commanding 
form  even  in  the  very  same  scene  in  which  in  ancient  art 
it  was  replaced  by  a  symbol.  This  likeness  of  Buddha 

aOp.  cit.,11,  p.is;. 


1 66  THE  MONIST. 

passed  with  Buddhism  from  Gandhara  into  all  foreign 
countries  which  Buddhism  conquered — into  central  Asia, 
China,  Japan  and  the  peninsula  of  Farther  India. 

That  this  surprising  change  which  marks  an  epoch  in 
Buddhist  art  can  not  be  explained  by  external  influences 
alone  is  obvious,  although  it  must  seem  very  natural  that 
the  artists  of  Gandhara  should  rely  upon  the  Greek  types 
already  known  to  them  when  they  felt  the  need  for  the 
production  of  religious  images.  But  these  models  would 
never  have  been  able  to  accomplish  this  revolution  alone. 
Such  a  change  presupposes  a  transformation  of  Buddhist 
doctrine.  In  the  original  Buddhism  Buddha  was  only  a 
man  who  by  his  own  power  had  found  salvation  from  the 
sorrows  of  continuous  existence  and  had  shown  the  way 
by  which  it  might  be  attained  by  everyone.  Here  there 
could  be  no  worship ;  here  the  teaching  was  more  important 
than  the  personality  of  the  teacher,  just  as  Buddha  him- 
self had  said  before  his  death  in  his  last  sermon:  "The 
Doctrine  and  the  Order  which  I  have  taught  and  pro- 
claimed unto  you  —  they  are  your  master  when  I  am 
gone."13  The  art  of  Gandhara  shows  that  the  personality 
of  Buddha  had  taken  the  place  of  the  Doctrine  and  had 
become  the  object  of  worship.  It  is  the  visible  witness 
of  a  transformation  of  fundamental  views  as  it  had  ad- 
vanced on  the  road  towards  the  Mahayana. 

Dahlmann's  line  of  argument,  however,  places  the 
greatest  value  on  the  role  played  in  the  Mahayana  by  the 
future  Buddha,  Maitreya.  As  we  are  later  to  criticise 
Dahlmann  specially  it  will  be  better  to  give  his  standpoint 
in  his  own  words.  For  this  reason  I  have  extracted  a  con- 
siderable passage  from  his  work  (II,  pp.  127,  128)  : 

"Many  other  Buddhas  at  long  intervals  had  preceded 
Gotama  Buddha  in  his  calling  as  teacher  of  mankind.  Go- 
tama  himself  as  the  twenty-fifth  was  claimed  to  have  com- 

13  Oldenberg,  Buddha,  5th  ed.,  p.  233. 


CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  CHRISTIANITY  TO  BUDDHISM.     167 

pleted  forever  the  series  of  the  teachers  of  mankind.  There- 
fore all  hope  of  salvation  was  based  on  the  doctrine  he 
proclaimed.  No  other  Buddha  was  to  be  expected  in  the 
future  as  teacher  of  salvation.  To  this  idea  a  newly  arisen 
school  (the  Mahayana)  took  exception,  in  so  far  as  it 
supplied  a  successor  as  teacher  of  salvation  to  the  Buddha 
now  worshiped ....  The  Buddha  Maitreya  constituted  the 
central  point  of  this  school.  The  earlier  tradition  knew 
nothing  of  Maitreya.  As  simple  as  it  would  have  been 
to  continue  to  spin  the  thread  of  the  Buddhas  reappearing 
at  periodical  intervals,  yet  the  myth  stood  still  at  Gotama 
as  the  last  Buddha.  Buddha  Maitreya  in  the  form  in  which 
he  is  transmitted  to  us  is  a  new  creation ....  But  in  the 
introduction  of  the  Buddha  Maitreya  we  have  not  merely 
to  do  with  a  new  Buddha.  Maitreya  became  the  center 
of  a  new  cult  in  a  character  fundamentally  different  from 
the  old  Buddha,  and  this  character  was  that  of  the  loving 
compassionate  Saviour  who  will  one  day  come  to  liberate 
the  world  from  the  bonds  of  suffering.  '  Herewith  there 
entered  into  this  doctrine  of  salvation  an  entirely  new  ele- 
ment in  contradiction  to  the  old  tradition.  It  directed  the 
cult  into  the  very  path  which  the  communities  of  monks 
had  always  resisted  hitherto.  The  teacher  becomes  a 
Saviour]  the  human  being,  a  divine  being  to  whom  man 
needs  only  to  turn  in  trustfulness  in  order  to  be  saved.  In 
other  words  it  is  the  Saviour-idea  as  incorporated  in  the 
Buddha  Maitreya  which  called  the  Mahayana  into  exist- 


ence." 


That  this  conception  of  Dahlmann  is  in  the  main  in- 
correct and  easily  disproved  we  shall  see  later  on.  At  pres- 
ent we  shall  anticipate  only  one  point.  It  must  be  granted 
that  in  the  Mahayana  a  different  character  is  assigned  to 
the  future  Buddha  Maitreya  than  formerly  to  the  real 
Buddha,  and  that  here  indeed  there  exists  a  new  element  of 
which  the  old  tradition  knew  nothing. 


l68  THE  MONIST. 

Dahlmann  thinks  that  this  new  element  can  be  explained 
only  by  foreign  influence,  and  to  him  the  only  foreign  in- 
fluence worthy  of  consideration  is  that  of  Christianity. 

The  ardent  joy  with  which  Dahlmann  proclaims  this 
presumed  discovery  is  easily  understood,  for  in  earlier 
works14  he  had  tried  to  explain  the  fall  of  Buddhism  in  its 
own  country  by  its  intrinsic  corruption.  How  well  did 
this  standpoint  seem  to  agree  with  the  knowledge,  which 
Dahlmann  thinks  he  has  gained,  that  Buddhism  does  not 
owe  its  triumphal  procession  through  central  and  eastern 
Asia  and  its  dispersion  over  a  third  of  all  mankind  to  its 
own  power  but  to  Christian  ideas  by  which  it  was  enriched 
in  northwestern  India  and  attained  its  peculiar  world- 
conquering  vitality !  Thus  it  would  not  be  Buddhism  which 
had  subjected  the  peoples  of  eastern  Asia  but  an  offshoot  of 
Christianity  in  Buddhist  garb. 

As  comprehensible  as  Dahlmann's  joy  in  his  discovery 
is  the  enthusiastic  applause  which  his  thesis  has  received 
from  some  quarters  of  the  Catholic  press.  Indeed,  the 
positiveness  of  the  assertion  and  the  brilliant  exposition  in 
which  Dahlmann  has  disposed  of  it  seemed  once  for  all  "to 
have  made  an  end  of  the  Buddhism  humbug."  When  we 
approach  Dahlmann's  spirited  demonstration  with  a  dis- 
passionate critique  it  vanishes  into  nothing. 

In  the  first  place,  what  is  the  chronological  possibility 
for  the  assumption  that  the  appearance  of  the  likeness  of 
Buddha  in  the  art  of  Gandhara,  the  divinity  of  Buddha 
as  attested  by  this  art,  and  the  conception  of  Maitreya 
as  a  divine  Saviour  can  be  explained  by  Christian  in- 
fluence ?  It  is  pretty  well  established  that  the  art  of  Gan- 
dhara reached  its  height  at  the  end  of  the  first  and  be- 
ginning of  the  second  century  A.  D.,  but  no  time  can  as  yet 
be  definitely  fixed  upon  for  its  beginning.  The  probability  is 

**  Nirvana,  eine  Studie  zur  Vorgeschichte  des  Buddhismus,  Berlin,  1896; 
Buddha,  ein  Kulturbild  des  Ostens,  Berlin,  1898. 


CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  CHRISTIANITY  TO  BUDDHISM.     169 

in  favor  of  the  pre-Christian  period.  The  best  specialists  in 
this  field,  Griinwedel  and  Aurel  Stein,  have  been  inclined  on 
account  of  the  new  discoveries  in  Turfan  and  Khotan  to 
place  the  beginning  of  the  Gandhara  art  in  the  first  or  per- 
haps even  in  the  second  century  before  Christ.15  And  the 
first  contemporary  expert  of  Northern  Buddhism,  Louis 
De  la  Vallee  Poussin,  has  practically  settled16  that  the 
deification  of  Buddha  in  mythology  and  religion  had  taken 
place  before  the  Christian  era. 

But  if  in  spite  of  this  we  take  Dahlmann's  standpoint 
that  the  religion  and  art  of  Gandhara  originated  in  the 
Christian  era  we  must  further  concede  to  him  that  Chris- 
tianity had  penetrated  as  early  as  the  first  century  into  the 
valleys  of  the  Kabul  and  Indus — an  assumption  whose 
"possibility  is  not  contested  to-day  in  any  quarter (  !)"17  Of 
course  Dahlmann  has  to  base  this  assumption  upon  a  de- 
fense of  the  historicity  of  the  St.  Thomas  legend  because 
he  needs  the  apostleship  of  St.  Thomas  in  the  Indo-Iranian 
territory  for  his  demonstration. 

Whereas  earlier  advocates  of  the  historical  character 
of  the  legend  of  St.  Thomas,  in  so  far  as  it  relates  to  the 
Indo-Iranian  territory,  based  their  thesis  upon  discoveries 
of  coins  and  one  inscription  by  which  the  king  in  the  Acts 
of  St.  Thomas,  Guduphara-Gondaphares,  was  proved  to 
belong  to  the  first  half  of  the  first  century  after  Christ,  as 
well  as  upon  reports  of  the  international  commercial  rela- 
tions of  that  day,  Dahlmann  brings  forward  the  combina- 
tion of  apostleship  and  art  in  the  person  of  St.  Thomas  as 
new  and  in  his  opinion  the  strongest  evidence  that  the 
Christian  influence  in  the  art  of  Gandhara  could  be  ex- 
plained through  the  activity  of  St.  Thomas  in  India.  This 
idea  must  be  objected  to  on  two  grounds :  ( i )  that  Christian 

"Wecker,  Tiibinger  Theol.  Quartalschrift,  92,  note  on  p.  432. 
uBouddhisme,  Opinions  sur  I'histoire  de  la  dogmatique,  Paris,  1909. 
17  Dahlmann,  II,  p.  138. 


I7O  THE  MONIST. 

influence  can  not  be  proved  in  the  art  of  Gandhara;  (2) 
that  in  the  legend  of  St.  Thomas,  as  O.  Wecker  justly  re- 
marks,18 "the  Christian  apostle  is  not  brought  into  relation 
with  that  kind  of  artistic  activity  which  most  clearly  be- 
trays the  connection  between  Gandhara  and  the  west,  that 
is  to  say  with  sculpture,  but  with  the  work  of  an  architect 
and  carpenter/'  which  may  probably  be  accounted  for  by 
the  imagery  of  the  construction  of  church  or  temple  cur- 
rent in  Christian  modes  of  speech.  Since  I  have  given  the 
reasons  in  this  periodical  (October  1911)  why  there  can 
be  no  question  of  an  historical  nucleus  in  the  Thomas 
legend,  but  that  on  the  contrary  Christianity  did  not  pene- 
trate into  northwestern  India  at  the  earliest  before  the 
beginning  of  the  third  century,  Dahlmann's  theory  becomes 
for  us  an  historical  impossibility. 

But  even  a  person  who  is  not  convinced  of  the  unhis- 
torical  character  of  the  legend  of  St.  Thomas  and  who 
accordingly  finds  no  difficulties  in  the  question  of  chronol- 
ogy to  prevent  him  from  following  Dahlmann's  lead,  can 
not  be  convinced  by  the  arguments  adduced  by  Dahlmann 
for  Christian  influence  on  the  art  and  religion  of  Gan- 
dhara, provided  he  understands  how  to  pursue  with  the 
correct  scientific  method  the  beginnings  of  the  development 
in  early  Buddhism  which  led  to  the  later  phenomenon  of 
the  Mahayana  in  dogma  and  worship.  This  has  been 
shown  very  clearly  by  O.  Wecker,19  who  nevertheless  re- 
gards the  historicity  of  the  fundamental  features  of  the 
Thomas  legend  as  possible.  To  him  everything  that  Dahl- 
mann understands  only  on  the  assumption  of  Christian  in- 
fluence is  to  be  accounted  for  quite  spontaneously  from  the 
natural  development  of  Buddhism.  Some  of  his  statements 
may  follow  here  in  his  own  words:20  "In  strange  contrast 
to  the  theoretical  universality  of  the  message  of  salvation, 

18  Tiibinger  Theol  Quartalschrift,  92,  note  on  p.  561. 
19Loc.  cit.,  pp.  441  ff. 
510  Pages  442-444- 


CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  CHRISTIANITY  TO  BUDDHISM. 

there  stood  from  the  beginning  the  difficulty  with  which 
the  redeeming  knowledge  is  to  be  gained,  a  difficulty  so 
great  that  in  fact  the  salvation  of  Buddha  could  never  be 
a  salvation  for  all,  especially  not  for  the  many  small  and 

poor  and  weak As  soon  as  the  consequences  were 

drawn  from  the  universality  of  the  salvation  which  Buddha 
preached,  the  exclusiveness  of  the  pure  Buddha  doctrine 
must  have  been  shattered;  the  postulates  and  ideas  must 
necessarily  be  leveled  and  accommodated  to  the  needs  of 
every-day  people  as  soon  as  the  sermon  becomes  serious 
with  its  'All  ye,  come  unto  me.'  Is  not  this  what  happened? 
We  need  only  point  to  the  transformation  of  the  Nirvana 
ideal21  to  illustrate  by  a  classical  example  the  process  of 
conversion  which  changed  the  pure  teaching  of  Buddha 
into  a  popular  religion....^  similar  transformation  of 
the  person  of  Buddha  was  the  natural  consequence  of  this 
evolution." 

The  transformation  of  the  Nirvana  concept,  which 
moreover  can  not  be  explained  solely  by  the  change  of 
the  original  doctrine  of  Buddha  into  a  folk-religion,  but 

21  When  speaking  in  this  essay  of  Nirvana  we  mean  salvation  after  death. 
Many  discussions  on  the  concept  of  Nirvana  suffer  greatly  from  lack  of  clear- 
ness for  the  reason  that  they  do  not  take  into  consideration  the  ambiguity  of 
the  word  Nirvana,  to  which  attention  has  been  called  first  by  Rhys  Davids 
(Buddhismus,  n8ff.)  and  later  by  Pischel  in  an  exhaustive  argument  (Leben 
und  Lehre  des  Buddha,  2d  ed.,  pp.  n  ff.).  Even  in  ancient  Buddhism  the  word 
Nirvana  was  used  not  only  in  the  sense  of  salvation  proper  which  took  place 
at  the  death  of  the  Perfect  One,  that  is  in  the  sense  of  annihilation  of  exist- 
ence, but  also  to  denote  salvation  during  life,  that  is  the  condition  of  complete 
rest  and  sinlessness  which  endures  until  death  and  is  brought  about  by  right- 
eous living  and  redeeming  knowledge.  In  distinction  from  this  "salvation 
during  life,"  which  has  also  been  a  very  current  idea  in  the  Brahman  systems 
from  pre-Buddhistic  times  until  to-day,  the  real  final  salvation  in  death  is  for 
the  sake  of  clearness  often  called  Parinirvana,  "perfect  Nirvana" ;  but  usually 
this  distinction  is  not  observed  by  the  language  in  the  texts. 

I  mention  here  this  ambiguity  in  the  Nirvana  concept  because  it  continues 
also  in  the  Mahayana.  What  Ashvaghosha  says  in  his  Awakening  of  Faith 
(Teitaro  Suzuki,  p.  87)  about  Nirvana  ("As  ignorance  is  thus  annihilated, 
the  mind  is  no  more  disturbed  so  as  to  be  subject  to  individuation.  As  the 
mind  is  no  more  disturbed  the  particularization  of  the  surrounding  world  is 
annihilated.  When  in  this  wise  the  principle  and  the  condition  of  defilement, 
their  products,  and  the  mental  disturbances  are  all  annihilated,  it  is  said  that 
we  attain  Nirvana"),  and  what  the  translator  (page  119  note)  gives  as  the 
general  conception  of  the  Mahayanists  on  the  four  stages  of  Nirvana  does  not 
refer  to  the  final  Nirvana  but  very  distinctly  to  Nirvana  during  life. 


172  THE  MONIST. 

also  by  the  progress  of  the  doctrine  among  more  active 
peoples  filled  with  different  desires  and  hopes,  would  ac- 
cording to  Dahlmann's  standpoint  have  to  be  referred  to 
Christian  influence,  but  strange  to  say  Dahlmann  has  laid 
no  stress  upon  the  transformation  of  the  Nirvana  ideal  in 
his  demonstration. 

The  deification  of  the  person  of  Buddha  becomes  com- 
prehensible from  the  natural  evolution  of  Buddhistic  doc- 
trine not  only  by  means  of  such  general  considerations  as 
those  we  have  just  discussed.  We  can  also22  discover 
quite  positive  starting  points  for  the  path  pursued  in  the 
alteration  of  the  concept  of  Buddha.  We  must  remember 
the  charm  exercised  by  the  personality  of  Buddha  upon 
his  environment,  and  the  reverence  which  was  shown  the 
master  and  which  of  course  increased  greatly  after  his 
death.  Even  in  the  formula  of  admission,  "I  take  my 
refuge  in  Buddha,  etc.,"  in  the  earliest  period  of  Bud- 
dhism the  person  of  the  founder  was  placed  before  the 
doctrine.  Then  the  worship  of  sacred  places  which  played 
a  role  of  particular  importance  in  Buddha's  life,  and  the 
worship  of  relics,  which  started  up  in  circles  of  the  laity 
immediately  after  his  death  must  have  contributed  to  the 
exaltation  of  his  person,  as  did  also  the  formation  of  leg- 
ends in  which  not  only  the  life  of  the  historical  Buddha 
but  also  all  the  former  existences  ascribed  to  him  were 
surrounded  by  the  creations  of  an  unchecked  fancy.  Even 
the  monuments  of  early  Buddhist  art  testify  that  the 
memory  of  the  founder  held  the  central  place  in  religious 
thought ;  for  although  the  likeness  of  Buddha  was  avoided 
(in  order  to  give  expression,  as  a  matter  of  principle,  to  the 
thought  that  the  doctrine  is  more  important  than  the 
teacher)  yet  in  reality  all  those  old  reliefs  are  "Buddha- 
centric."23 

M  With  Wecker,  pp.  445  ff . 
"Wecker,  p.  451. 


CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  CHRISTIANITY  TO  BUDDHISM.     173 

Wecker  is  right  however  in  laying  most  emphasis  upon 
the  speculative  and  dogmatic  development  of  the  old  Bud- 
dhism. If  the  form  of  the  one  historical  Buddha  here  be- 
comes multiplied,  further  if  beside  those  Buddhas  (called 
in  Sanskrit  pratyeka-,  in  Pali  pacceka-Buddhas}  who  are 
capable  of  attaining  saving  knowledge  only  for  themselves 
but  have  not  the  ability  to  bring  salvation  to  others,  there 
appear  the  samyak-  (Pali  samma-}  sambuddhas,  the  holy 
universal  Buddhas  who  appear  at  definite  times  in  the  var- 
ious ages  of  the  world  in  this  and  in  other  worlds  with 
quite  decided  powers  and  signs  in  order  to  preach  the  sav- 
ing knowledge,  then  already  "Buddha's  form  in  the  belief 
of  the  Order  had  exceeded  the  limits  of  earthly  human  re- 
ality."5 This  elevation  into  the  sphere  of  the  supernatural 
may  also  have  been  favored  by  such  stories  as  that  of  the 
conversation  with  the  Brahman  Dona25  in  which  Buddha 
expressly  states  that  men  who  have  attained  Buddhahood 
form  a  special  category  of  beings  different  from  gods, 
demigods  and  men. 

With  the  multiplication  of  the  historical  Buddha  there 
grew  up  the  faith  in  future  Buddhas  for  which  there  is 
evidence  in  the  canonical  Pali  literature.26  The  dogma  of 
the  Buddha  of  the  future  is  explained  as  readily  as  the 
deification  of  the  historical  Buddha  from  the  evolution  of 
the  Buddhist  religion.  At  the  same  time  we  do  not  deny 
that  in  the  formation  of  the  ideas  of  the  future  Buddha 
analogous  foreign  elements  have  cooperated.  If  the  his- 
torical possibility  and  probability  of  such  an  influence  must 
be  admitted,  it  even  becomes  very  credible.  Dahlmann27 

**Oldenberg,  Buddha,  5th  ed.,  p.  382;  English  translation  by  Wm.  Hoey, 
P-  325. 

*H.  Kern,  Manual  of  Indian  Buddhism  (Grundriss  der  indoarischen 
Philologie  und  Altertumskunde,  II,  8)  p.  64. 

"In  the  Mahaparinibbanasutta,  Dighanikaya,  XVI,  i,  16,  (in  the  Rhys 
Davids-Carpenter  edition,  II,  p.  82)  according  to  a  kind  communication  from 
O.  Franke. 

"II,  pp.  131-134- 


174  THE  MONIST. 

takes  action  with  great  energy  but  with  quite  inadequate 
grounds  against  the  theory  that  the  Iranian  ideas  of  the 
future  Saviour,  the  Saoshyant  (later  Sosiosh)  could  have 
influenced  the  thought-cycle  of  the  Mahayana.  And  yet 
nothing  is  more  obvious  than  this,  since  we  are  dealing 
with  a  time  in  which  Iranian  influences  upon  northwestern 
India  have  been  plentifully  established,  as  shown  for  in- 
stance on  the  coins  of  the  Gandhara  period.28 

Even  in  the  Mahayana  speculations  on  the  five  Dhyani- 
buddhas,  the  "Buddhas  arisen  from  meditation,"  which 
are  reflexes  of  the  earthly  Buddhas  in  transcendent  worlds, 
the  influence  has  been  recognized  of  the  Iranian  doctrine 
of  the  Fravashis,  those  prototypes  of  all  good  creatures 
existing  from  eternity  to  eternity. 

The  main  point  against  Dahlmann's  theory,  which 
brings  the  whole  artificial  structure  to  the  ground  at  one 
stroke  and  which,  strange  to  say,  has  been  overlooked  by 
Wecker,  I  have  saved  until  the  last.  The  foundation  upon 
which  Dahlmann's  demonstration  rests  consists  of  the 
statement  that  the  older  tradition  does  not  know  anything 
at  all  of  Maitreya,  but  that  he  is  a  new  creation  of  the 
Mahayana.  This  assertion  is  also  found  elsewhere.  Griin- 
wedel29  has  the  following  to  say  about  Maitreya:  'The 
northern  school  is  acquainted  with  him  in  full  detail  and 
puts  revelations  in  his  mouth ;  yes,  he  is  everywhere  highly 
venerated,  almost  more  than  Gautama.  In  the  southern 
canon,  as  far  as  I  can  see,  he  does  not  appear,  although 
the  Singhalese  chronicle  Mahavansa  is  acquainted  with 
him."30  Similarly  we  read  in  the  supplemental  volume  of 

28  Wecker,  loc.  cit.,  pp.  439,  440,  455.  Griinwedel,  Buddhistische  Kunst, 
2d.  ed.,  p.  167:  "Hence  we  are  perhaps  justified  in  pointing  out  that  here 
again  contact  with  Iranian  ideas  has  taken  place.  The  similarity  of  the  idea 
of  the  future  Buddha  Maitreya  with  the  Saviour  of  the  Parsi  religion  Sao- 
shyant (Sosiosh}  is  very  striking.  Although  we  do  not  know  when  the 
legend  of  the  Saoshyant  as  it  now  exists  developed  among  the  Iranians  yet 
the  dominant  position  of  the  Maitreya  within  the  northern  church  has  cer- 
tainly been  influenced  by  it." 

39  Buddhistische  Kunst,  2d  ed.,  p.  158. 

30  Except  the  later  continuations,  it  dates  from  the  end  of  the  fifth  cen- 


CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  CHRISTIANITY  TO  BUDDHISM. 

Brockhaus's  Konversationslexikon  (i4th  edition)  in  the 
article  "Buddhismus,"  page  2290,  on  Maitreya  (Pali,  Met- 
teyya) :  "The  southern  church  acknowledges  him  but  the 
canonical  writings  do  not  mention  him.  The  Mahayana 
school  which  originated  in  the  north  betakes  itself  with 
peculiar  zeal  to  the  Maitreya  cult  and  other  Bodhisatvas." 
Of  these  two  sentences  only  the  second  one  is  correct.  A 
glance  into  the  best  known  work  on  Buddhism31  shows  that 
the  idea  of  the  future  Buddha  Metteyya  was  not  unknown 
to  ancient  Buddhism.  T.  W.  Rhys  Davids  also  says  ex- 
pressly that  this  doctrine  already  forms  part  of  the  system 
of  the  Small  Vehicle  (Hinayana).32 

The  passage  cited  by  Oldenberg  (loc.  cit.)  is  taken  from 
the  Cakkavattisuttanta,  a  part  of  the  Dighanikaya  and 
hence  belonging  to  the  canonical  Pali  literature.  It  reads : 
"He  will  be  the  leader  of  a  band  of  disciples  containing 
hundreds  of  thousands  as  I  now  am  the  leader  of  a  band  of 
hundreds."33 

Further,  Metteyya  is  called  the  future  Buddha  in  the 
Buddhavamsa  (27.  19), 34  a  short  poetical  biography  of 
the  twenty-four  former  Buddhas  which  belongs  to  the  ap- 
pendices of  the  Suttapitaka.  According  to  the  preceding 
verse  Kakusandha,  Konagamana  and  Kassapa  were  enu- 
merated as  the  three  Buddhas  preceding  the  historical 
Buddha  in  this  "blessed  eon"  (bhaddaka  kappa).  Now  to 
be  sure,  as  the  editor  observes,  the  Buddhavamsa  orig- 

tury  after  Christ.  (See  the  citations  for  Metteyya  in  Childers's  Dictionary  of 
the  Pali  Language}.  Metteyya  is  moreover  mentioned  also  in  the  Milinda- 
panha,  p.  159,  which  probably  belongs  to  the  second  century  after  Christ. 

"Oldenberg,  Buddha,  5th  ed.,  p.  164,  note;  384  note  i. 

sa  Der  Buddhismus,  translated  into  German  by  A.  Pf ungst,  Leipsic,  p.  208. 

88  Dighanikaya,  Sutta  26.  Even  a  scholar  so  familiar  with  canonical  Pali 
literature  as  Prof.  O.  Franke  considers  this  passage  above  suspicion  and  de- 
clares it  to  be  impossible  that  it  could  have  been  interpolated  in  post-Christian 
times.  Compare  further  C.  A.  F.  Rhys  Davids's  review  of  Carpenter's  edition 
of  the  Dighanikaya,  Vol.  Ill,  Journal  of  the  Royal  Asiatic  Society,  1911,  p. 
557.  Professor  Oldenberg  has  kindly  called  my  attention  to  part  of  the  follow- 
ing passages. 

84  Page  67  of  Morris's  edition,  Pali  Text  Society. 


176  THE  MONIST. 

inally  ended  with  verse  18,  and  hence  the  two  following 
verses  and  the  last  song  (28)  would  be  a  later  addition; 
but  verse  19  only  contains  expressly  stated  what  was  al- 
ready implied  in  the  eighteenth  verse.  For  according  to 
the  Buddhist  doctrine  there  are  not  four  but  five  Buddhas 
in  a  bhadda  kappa  (Sanskrit,  bhadra  kalpa) ;  hence  the 
mention  of  such  a  kappa  implies  the  expectation  of  the 
fifth  Buddha.35  The  eons  are  divided  into  "void"  (San- 
skrit, shilnya;  Pali,  sunna)  in  which  no  Buddha  appears, 
and  "not-void"  (Sanskrit,  ashunya;  Pali,  asunna),  that 
is,  full  periods  in  which  there  are  one  or  more  Buddhas. 
The  not-void  eons  bear  special  names  according  to  the 
number  of  the  Buddhas  which  appear  in  them  (from  one 
to  five).36  A  bhadda  kappa  with  five  Buddhas  like  the 
present  one  always  comes  only  after  a  long  interval. 

We  have  no  reason  to  doubt  that  this  entire  idea  of  the 
different  kinds  of  eons  and  the  "eons  blessed"  with  five 
Buddhas  belonged  to  Buddhism  before  its  development 
into  the  Mahayana.  And  since  the  name  Maitreya-Met- 
teyya,  which  from  what  we  have  said  must  be  old  (belong- 
ing to  about  the  fourth  century  before  Christ),  is  derived 
from  the  Sanskrit  maitri  (Pali,  metta)  "love,"  so  we  can 
conclude  that  even  in  olden  times  the  idea  of  loving  com- 
passion was  bound  up  with  that  of  the  future  Buddha. 

We  see  that  there  is  hardly  a  question  in  the  history 
of  religion  which  can  be  decided  with  greater  certainty 
than  that  raised  by  Dahlmann  and  decided  without  any 
doubt,  according  to  his  opinion,  in  the  opposite  sense.  The 
Mahayana  has  arisen  without  any  influence  on  the  part  of 
Christianity  and  has  overcome  the  eastern  Asiatic  world 
by  its  own  power  in  a  mighty  triumphal  procession,  and 

"Oldenberg,  Buddha,  5th  ed.,  p.  384,  Note  i;  Koppen,  Die  Religion  des 
Buddha,  I,  p.  315. 

86  Spence  Hardy,  A  Manual  of  Buddhism,  p.  8 ;  Childers's  Dictionary  of 
the  Pali  Language,  s.  v.  "Kappo,"  p.  186;  Pischel,  Leben  und  Lehre  des 
Buddha,  2d  ed.,  p.  94, 


CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  CHRISTIANITY  TO  BUDDHISM.     177 

at  the  same  time  to  be  sure  without  shedding  a  drop  of 
blood,  solely  by  the  power  of  conviction  and  example.  How 
great  an  influence,  lasting  even  down  to  the  present  day, 
the  Mahayana  has  exerted  on  the  higher  spiritual  develop- 
ment of  China,  we  learn  from  the  great  sinologist  J.  J. 
M.  de  Groot  who  lived  in  China  for  years  among  Buddhist 
monks  and  who  declared  that  the  Buddhists  were  the  only 
Chinese  who  possessed  refinement  of  heart,  and  the  only 
ones  with  whom  one  could  discuss  spiritual  matters.37 

If  we  now  turn  to  the  question  whether  at  a  later  date 
the  demonstrable  contacts  with  Christianity  have  left  ap- 
preciable traces  on  northern  Buddhism,  I  am  inclined  to 
answer  in  the  affirmative,  although  it  is  difficult  to  give  a 
positive  proof. 

Before  I  enter  upon  the  subject  of  the  Buddhism  of 
Tibet,  which  here  comes  mainly  into  consideration,  I  shall 
add  an  incidental  remark. 

To  the  best  known  writings  of  the  Mahayana  literature 
belong  the  "Lotus  of  the  Good  Law"  and  the  biographies 
of  Buddha  called  Lalitavistara  and  Mahavastu,  none  of 
which  can  be  placed  before  200  A.  D.  Most  of  the  paral- 
lels with  the  Gospel  stories  which  have  been  met  with  in 
Buddhist  literature  are  found  in  these  three  works38  (and 
besides  in  the  Pali  Nidanakatha,  the  introduction  to  the 
Jataka  book,  dating  from  the  fifth  century  after  Christ). 

Nothing  more  can  now  be  said  about  these  parallels 
except  that  it  is  not  impossible  that  they  were  borrowed 
from  Christianity.  When  in  the  later  Mahayana  writings 
mention  is  made  of  Buddha  as  a  fisherman  who  catches 
men  like  fishes,  and  this  comparison  has  passed  over  into 
Chinese  art  in  which  Buddha  is  represented  as  a  fisherman 
with  rod  and  hook,39  we  cannot  fail  to  recognize  here  a 

87  See  Edv.  Lehmann,  Der  Buddhismus,  p.  256. 

"The  Monist,  XXI,  October  1911,  p.  520. 

89  Paul  Carus,  The  Open  Court,  June  1911,  p.  357. 


IjS  THE  MONIST. 

transference  of  the  Christian  symbol  into  the  Buddhist 
world,  because  the  catching  of  fish  is  an  entirely  un-Bud- 
dhistic  act.  The  same  is  true  of  the  typical  representation 
of  the  mother  with  the  child  Buddha.  That  this  goes  back 
to  Christian  prototypes  one  glance  at  the  "Buddhist  Ma- 
donna" from  Chinese  Turkestan  in  the  Ethnological  Mu- 
seum at  Berlin,  is  sufficient  to  prove.40 

For  such  transmissions  the  conditions  of  those  days 
were  particularly  favorable.  Kennedy  mentions,41  al- 
though without  stating  his  source,  that  in  the  eighth 
century  a  Christian  monk  and  a  Bactrian  Buddhist  to- 
gether composed  a  Christian-Buddhist  text-book.  The  fact 
is  that  in  Singan-fu,  the  ancient  capital  of  China,  the  Nes- 
torian  missionary  Adam,  the  "presbyter,  chorepiscopus  and 
papas  of  China" — called  by  the  Chinese  King  Tsing,  the 
"distinguished  and  pure  one" — together  with  Prajfia,  a 
Buddhist  from  Kapisha  in  Northern  India,  translated  into 
Chinese  the  Buddhist  Shatparamitasutra  from  the  Uigu- 
rischen.42  Through  the  famous  Chinese-Syriac  inscription 
of  Singan-fu,  written  in  the  year  781  by  the  above  men- 
tioned Adam  with  the  aid  of  other  Nestorians,  we  further 
learn  that  at  that  time  in  a  monastery  in  that  vicinity  Bud- 
dhist monks  and  Nestorian  Christians  were  living  and 
working  together  side  by  side  in  a  spirit  of  comradeship.43 
Such  friendly  intercourse  between  Buddhists  and  Chris- 
tians probably  existed  in  many  places  in  central  Asia  in 
those  times. 

Buddhism  did  not  penetrate  into  the  icy  highland  of 

40  See  frontispiece  in  A.  Foucher's  Beginnings  of  Buddhist  Art  and  Other 
Essays  on  Indian  and  Central  Asian  Archeology,  translated  by  L.  A.  and  W. 
F.  Thomas.  Paris,  1912. 

"Journal  of  the  Royal  Asiatic  Society,  1907,  p.  481. 

^Takakusu,  T'oung  Tao  VII,  1897,  pp.  589-591;  Berthold  Laufer,  The 
Open  Court,  August,  1911,  pp.  451-452.  According  to  this  the  emperor  Tai- 
Tsung  (780-804)  distinctly  issued  a  warning  against  the  confusion  of  Chris- 
tian and  Buddhist  doctrines. 

"Max  Miiller  Last  Essays,  I,  p.  258;  II,  pp.  310  ff.,  according  to  James 
Legge,  Christianity  in  China,  1888. 


CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  CHRISTIANITY  TO  BUDDHISM.     179 

Tibet  in  the  form  of  the  Mahayana  but  of  the  Yogachara 
system,44  which  indeed  wishes  to  be  recognized  as  only  a 
particular  school  of  the  Mahayana  and  which  according  to 
its  own  text-books  is  also  called  the  Tantra  school.  This 
school  was  founded  in  the  sixth  century  by  the  monk  Arya- 
sanga  of  Peshawar,  who  adopted  the  Brahman — especially 
the  Shivaitic — gods  into  Buddhism  as  defenders  of  the 
church  against  the  world  of  demons,  and  furnished  the 
religion  with  a  confused  theory  of  witchcraft  in  which 
predominated  mystical  formulas  (dharani)  for  the  attain- 
ment of  supernatural  powers  and  the  accomplishment  of  all 
possible  desires. 

In  this  degenerate  form  Buddhism  reached  Tibet  in  the 
middle  of  the  seventh  century,45  and  about  a  century  later 
the  church  known  under  the  name  Lamaism,  which  soon 
developed  into  an  ecclesiastical  state,  was  founded  by  the 
artful  "conjurer""  Padmasambhava  whom  the  Indian  mis- 
sionaries of  Buddhism  called  to  Tibet  from  his  native  land 
Kafiristan  in  order  to  overcome  the  opposition  of  the  native 
Shamans.46  Padmasambhava  succeeded  in  this  conquest 
by  incorporating  the  teachings  and  usages  of  these  Sha- 
mans, who  had  great  influence  among  the  people,  into 
Tibetan  Buddhism  in  which  since  that  time  they  have 
formed  an  important  component  part. 

The  possibility  of  Christian  influence  upon  Buddhism 
in  Tibet  and  China  has  existed  since  635,  for  from  this 
year  we  have  evidence  of  a  Nestorian  mission  which  set  out 
for  those  lands  under  a  leader  by  the  name  of  Olopan  or 
Alopen.47  This  mission  was  received  in  northern  India 

"  Literally,  "practice  of  witchcraft,"  the  chief  characteristic  of  this  school. 

"Griinwedel,  "Der  Lamaismus,"  p.  141,  (In  Hinneberg's  Kultur  der 
Gegenwart,  Part  I,  Section  III,  i:  "Die  Orientalischen  Religionen."  Berlin 
and  Leipsic,  1906.) 

46  Ibid.,  p.  143.  L.  Austine  Waddell,  The  Buddhism  of  Tibet  or  Lamaism, 
London,  1895,  PP-  x,  24  ff. ;  see  index. 

"  Waddell,  op.  cit.,  p.  422. 


180  THE  MONIST. 

by  the  famous  king  Shiladitya  at  his  court  in  Kanoj  in  the 
year  639** 

Later  there  arose  in  Nepal  and  Tibet  the  belief  in  the 
Adibuddha,  that  is,  in  an  omnipotent  and  omniscient  pri- 
meval Buddha,  who  was  supposed  to  have  begotten  the 
above-mentioned  five  Dhyanibuddhas  by  his  meditation— 
hence  a  monotheistic  transformation  of  the  original  atheistic 
Buddhism.  Rhys  Davids,49  following  Csoma  de  Koros, 
places  the  rise  of  this  faith  in  the  tenth  century,  L.  de  la 
Vallee  Poussin50  somewhat  earlier.  At  any  rate  H.  Kern 
and  Waddell,51  who  rests  upon  his  authority,  are  wrong  in 
placing  the  beginnings  of  the  doctrine  of  the  Adibuddha 
as  early  as  the  first  century  after  Christ. 

Poussin  regards  this  entirely  theistic  (aishvarika)  Bud- 
dhism, which  may  be  divided  into  several — at  least  into 
two — different  Adibuddha  systems,  merely  as  a  final  stage 
in  the  evolution  of  the  Mahayana.  He  says  :52  "Buddhist  in 
fact  only  in  name  and  in  so  far  as  it  employs  Buddhist 
terminology,  it  nevertheless  is,  as  it  were,  the  consumma- 
tion of  the  philosophical,  mystical  and  mythological  specu- 
lations of  the  Great  Vehicle,  and  differs  from  several  other 
systems  widespread  in  the  Buddhist  world,  only  by  its 
markedly  'theistic'  coloring."  He  mentions  relations  with 
Hinduism  but  never  even  alludes  to  the  possibility  of  Chris- 
tian influence.  We  shall  have  to  concede  to  him  that  to 
insert  a  personal  God,  inactive  in  principle  but  in  reality 
looked  upon  as  creative — and  as  such  we  must  consider 
Adibuddha — into  the  fantastic  system  of  the  later  Maha- 

"Takakusu,  I-Tsing  XXVIII,  note  8;  Athenaeum,  July  3,  1880,  p.  8  in 
the  review  of  Edkins's  Chinese  Buddhism;  Grierson,  Encyclopaedia  of  Re- 
ligion and  Ethics,  II,  p.  548  b. 

*•  Buddhismus,  p.  214. 

60  In  the  scholarly  and  exhaustive  article  "Adibuddha,"  Enc.  of.  Rel  and 
Eth.,  i,  pp.  93  ff.,  at  the  end  of  which  is  appended  a  comprehensive  bibliog- 
raphy. 

51  Buddhism  of  Tibet,  pp.  126,  130. 
M  Loc.  cit.,  p.  93  b. 


CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  CHRISTIANITY  TO  BUDDHISM.     l8l 

yana  is  quite  comprehensible  without  foreign  influence.  As 
at  first  the  imaginary  Dhyanibuddhas  and  Dhyanibodhi- 
sattvas  had  been  placed  above  the  earthly  Buddha  and  his 
many  manifestations  in  the  past  and  future,  which  had 
been  accounted  for  as  their  earthly  reflections,  so  later  a 
basis  might  be  sought  from  which  those  imaginary  figures 
could  be  deduced,  and  this  basis  might  be  found  in  a  su- 
preme God.  It  is  also  conceivable  that  the  desire  to  obtain 
adherents  for  the  Buddhist  religion  among  theistically  in- 
clined circles  has  contributed  to  the  production  of  the  Adi- 
buddha.  Poussin  might  have  pointed  out  an  analogous 
phenomenon  in  the  history  of  Brahman  philosophy,  namely 
the  introduction  of  the  personal  God  (ishvara)  into  the 
atheistic  Samkhya  system,  which  in  a  less  indirect  manner 
was  adopted  in  the  formation  of  this  system  into  the  Yoga 
doctrine.  Nevertheless  it  must  be  repeated  that  the  con- 
ception of  the  Adibuddha  may  possibly  be  reducible  to 
Christian  influence  since  in  Tibetan  Buddhism  religious 
discussions  with  Nestorians  had  undoubtedly  preceded  it 
in  point  of  time. 

With  greater  distinctness  we  can  recognize  the  often 
alleged  Christian  influences  on  the  later  development  of 
the  Lamaistic  form  of  worship  which  has  been  called  a 
caricature  of  the  Catholic  service.  Yet  Catholic  mission- 
aries who  had  penetrated  as  far  as  Tibet  have  reported 
with  horror  that  the  devil  had  created  a  caricature  of  the 
ritual  of  the  Roman  Catholic  church  there  in  order  to  bring 
it  into  derision. 

From  Grunwedel's  excellent  exposition  of  Lamaism53 
we  learn  that  the  European  Christian  mission  had  exerted 
itself  in  behalf  of  Tibet  ever  since  the  first  half  of  the  four- 
teenth century.  In  the  year  1330  Odoricus  of  Pordenone, 

"In  Hinneberg's  Kultur  der  Gegenwart,  Part  I,  Sec.  Ill,  I:  "Die  orien- 
talischen  Religionen,"  pp.  136  ff. ;  X,  "Europaische  Reisende  in  Tibet,"  pp. 
156  ff.  See  also  O.  Wecker,  Lamaismus  und  Katholizismus,  ein  Vortrag. 
Rottenburg,  1910;  and  Hackmann,  Buddhism  as  a  Religion,  pp.  71  ff.,  154  ff. 


1 82  THE  MONIST. 

the  first  European  who  had  succeeded  in  reaching  the  place, 
found  Christian  missionaries  and  some  converts  already 
in  the  capital  of  Tibet, — that  is,  in  Lhasa.  At  any  rate  we 
must  understand  these  missionaries  to  be  Syrian  Chris- 
tians. In  1624  after  a  long  interval  the  Portuguese  Jesuit 
d'Andrada,  coming  from  Delhi  to  the  city  of  Chaprang  in 
western  Tibet,  was  received  with  honor  by  the  ruling  king 
and  with  his  permission  laid  the  corner-stone  for  a  Chris- 
tian church.  We  learn  then  of  a  series  of  other  mission- 
aries, Dominicans  and  Jesuits,  from  the  beginning  of  the 
eighteenth  century,  of  many  hardships  with  which  they  had 
to  contend,  but  also  of  protection  and  benevolence  on  the 
part  of  the  king.  In  1719  begins  the  missionary  activity 
of  the  Capuchins,  who  had  been  successful  at  Rome  in 
having  the  monopoly  of  the  Tibetan  mission  conferred 
upon  them.  It  was  at  once  taken  in  .charge  by  the  Capu- 
chins to  a  much  greater  extent.  In  the  same  year  Horatio 
della  Penna  came  to  Tibet  with  twelve  Capuchins,  again 
in  1737  with  nine,  since  most  of  his  first  companions  had 
died  or  had  become  incapable  of  work.  But  towards  the 
middle  of  the  eighteenth  century,  soon  after  the  death  of 
Horatio,  the  Capuchins  gave  up  the  evangelization  of 
Tibet. 

We  have  no  knowledge  of  any  success  their  exertions 
may  have  had.  If  they  had  made  converts  to  any  con- 
siderable extent,  surely  all  accounts  of  them  could  not 
have  been  so  lost  as  to  leave  no  trace.  The  missionaries 
were  apparently  wise  enough  to  judge  the  matter  correctly 
and  to  recognize  the  hopelessness  of  any  considerable  ex- 
tension of  Christianity  in  Tibet.  But  from  the  syncretistic 
character  of  Lamaism,  which  had  adopted  not  only  the 
Brahman  gods  but  also  the  national  divinities  of  the  Tib- 
etans and  finally  after  the  conversion  of  the  Mongols  even 
some  of  their  ideas,  they  must  also  have  been  justified  in 


CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  CHRISTIANITY  TO  BUDDHISM.     183 

expecting  there  would  be  room  within  it  for  Christian  ideas 
and  Christian  forms  of  worship  as  well. 

With  a  similar  view  the  Jesuits  in  China  who  had  come 
in  1581  under  the  leadership  of  Ricci  in  the  garb  of  Bud- 
dhist monks  in  order  to  secure  a  kindly  reception,  started 
out  towards  the  end  of  the  sixteenth  century,  and  while 
publicly  participating  in  Confucian  worship  diffused  Chris- 
tian ideas  so  that  many  Chinese  accepted  Christianity,  but 
did  not  for  that  reason  cease  being  Confucianists,  Taoists 
or  Buddhists,  until  finally  a  peremptory  order  from  Rome 
put  an  end  to  this  adjustment  of  Christianity  to  Chinese 
requirements.54  So  the  Christian  missionaries  in  Tibet 
would  naturally  have  aimed  upon  the  whole  at  the  peace- 
ful infiltration  of  Christian  ideas  into  Lamaism  in  the  hope 
of  imperceptibly  Christianizing  it  in  time.  That  they  suc- 
ceeded better  in  this  with  regard  to  forms  of  worship  than 
doctrine  may  be  explained  by  the  fact  that  Lamaism  in 
contrast  to  the  original  Buddhism  was  directed  essentially 
to  externalities.  In  the  high  value  placed  upon  sanctimoni- 
ous observance  Lamaism  and  Catholicism  must  have  met 
on  the  same  level. 

In  the  year  1760  Tibet  closed  its  doors  to  European 
visitors,  and  since  that  time  only  isolated  Europeans — 
usually  in  the  dress  of  Asiatics — have  succeeded  in  pene- 
trating into  that  country,  but  without  reaching  the  capital 
Lhasa,  with  the  exception  of  the  British  expedition  under 
Colonel  Younghusband,  whose  entry  into  Lhasa  in  the  year 
1904  is  still  fresh  in  our  memories. 

At  any  rate  the  seclusion  of  Tibet  was  complete  when 
the  two  Lazarist  fathers  Hue  and  Gabet,  in  the  garb  of 
Buddhist  ecclesiastics,  arrived  at  Lhasa  from  Mongolia 
in  January  1846  after  a  toilsome  journey  of  a  year  and  a 
half,  and  were  compelled  to  leave  again  in  March  upon  the 
demand  of  the  Chinese  Resident.  The  information  which 

64  Max  Muller,  Last  Essays,  II,  pp.  315-317. 


184  THE  MONIST. 

Hue  has  given  in  his  famous  book55  on  Lamaistic  forms  of 
worship  is  an  important  source  for  all  who  have  written  on 
Lamaism. 

Rhys  Davids's  Buddhism  closes  with  the  following  com- 
prehensive description :  "Lamaism,  indeed,  with  its  shaven 
priests,  its  bells,  and  rosaries,  its  images,  and  holy  water, 
and  gorgeous  dresses ;  its  service  with  double  choirs,  and 
processions  and  creeds,  and  mystic  rites,  and  incense,  in 
which  the  laity  are  spectators  only;  its  abbots  and  monks, 
and  nuns  of  many  grades;  its  worship  of  the  double  vir- 
gin, and  of  the  saints  and  angels;  its  fasts,  confessions 
and  purgatory,  its  images,  its  idols  and  its  pictures;  its 
huge  monasteries  and  its  gorgeous  cathedrals,  its  powerful 
hierarchy,  its  cardinals,  its  pope,  bears  outwardly  at  least, 
a  strong  resemblance  to  Romanism,  in  spite  of  the  essen- 
tial difference  of  its  teachings  and  of  its  mode  of  thought." 

This  description  could  be  further  supplemented  by  ref- 
erence to  the  crozier  and  the  bishop's  mitre,  exorcism  of 
demons,  the  censer  with  five  chains  which  can  be  closed 
or  opened  at  will,  the  benediction  in  which  the  Lama  lays 
his  right  hand  upon  the  head  of  the  believer,  the  religious 
exercises  in  seclusion,  and  still* other  particulars.56  Further- 
more the  practice  of  the  higher  Lamas  to  cross  themselves 
before  the  beginning  of  a  religious  service57  seems  to  me 
to  deserve  special  mention,  as  does  also  a  ceremony  which 
bears  a  remarkable  resemblance  to  the  celebration  of  the 
Lord's  Supper.58  In  this  we  have  the  distribution  of  con- 
secrated bread  and  wine  to  the  devout  congregation.  In 
place  of  the  bread  consecrated  pellets  of  puff-paste  are  also 
mentioned,  and  by  wine  we  must  probably  understand  a 

55  Souvenirs  d'un  voyage  dans  la  Tartarie,  le  Tibet  et  la  Chine,  2  vols. 
Paris,  1850  (second  edition,  1853)  ;  English  edition,  Chicago,  Open  Court  Pub- 
lishing Company. 

M  Hue  in  Wecker,  loc.  cit.,  p.  37. 

67  Waddell,  Buddhism  of  Tibet,  p.  423. 

68  Ibid.,  pp.  444  ff. 


CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  CHRISTIANITY  TO  BUDDHISM.     185 

different  sort  of  alcoholic  drink.59  At  any  rate  "bread  and 
wine"  are  enjoyed  by  the  participants  in  this  ceremony 
"for  the  attainment  of  long  life."  By  long  life  may  be 
understood  a  circumlocution  for  the  Christian  idea  of 
eternal  life. 

One  other  fundamental  idea  of  Lamaism  appeals  to  us 
as  strictly  Catholic,  namely  that  the  priests  "hold  the  keys 
of  hell  and  heaven,  for  they  have  invented  the  common 
saying:  Without  a  Lama  in  front  (of  the  votary)  there 
is  no  (approach  to)  God/"60 

One  might  be  tempted  to  account  for  these  correspon- 
dences between  Catholic  and  Lamaistic  worship  as  parallel 
phenomena  by  the  statement  that  the  human  mind  when 
moved  in  the  same  direction  of  thought  arid  feeling  arrives 
externally  at  the  same  results.  But  the  correspondences 
are  too  close  and  too  numerous  for  us  to  get  along  without 
the  assumption  of  a  loan.  As  at  the  close  of  my  former 
essay  in  this  periodical  (October,  1911)  on  "Contributions 
of  Buddhism  to  Christianity"  I  could  not  avoid  the  con- 
viction that  many  fundamental  features  in  the  worship  of 
the  early  Christian  church  have  been  taken  over  from  Bud- 
dhism, so  on  the  other  hand  at  a  more  recent  date  many 
Christian  forms  of  worship  of  a  later  stage  of  development 
have  found  acceptance  in  the  most  degenerate  form  of  Bud- 
dhism, Lamaism. 

I  have  pointed  out  above  (pp.  182-183)  how  in  my 
opinion  this  has  come  about.  Hue  has  called  attention 
to  still  another  possibility.61  In  the  thirteenth  century  in 
the  times  of  the  Mongolian  supremacy,  ambassadors  from 
the  rulers  of  the  world  came  to  Italy,  Spain,  France  and 
England,  and  took  home,  so  Hue  thinks,  a  deep  impression 
of  the  glitter  and  splendor  of  the  Catholic  worship.  Per- 

68  "Ambrosia  brewed  from  spirit  or  beer,"  Waddell,  p.  445 ;  in  the  middle 
of  page  448  he  speaks  again  of  the  sacred  wine. 
60  Ibid.,  pp.  422-423. 
81  In  Wecker,  Lamaismus  und  Katholizismus,  pp.  37-39. 


l86  THE  MONIST. 

haps  they  did;  but  the  incidental  enthusiastic  descriptions 
of  these  secular  ambassadors  would  have  assumed  only 
very  general  outlines  and  could  hardly  have  exercised  any 
influence  on  the  later  worship  of  the  Mongols.  Still  less 
propable  is  it  that  the  Mongols  would  have  carried  traces 
of  this  influence  to  Tibet,  since  indeed  they  took  Lamaism 
away  from  Tibet  with  them  and  have  remained  its  true 
devotees  until  the  present  day.  Moreover,  at  the  time  of 
their  greatest  power  the  Mongols,  who  were  then  adherents 
of  Shamanism,  were  religiously  indifferent,  and  ambassa- 
dors of  Buddhism,  of  Islam  and  even  of  Christianity  waited 
upon  them  in  vain.  When  Kubilai  Khan  was  converted 
to  Buddhism  in  the  thirteenth  century  the  Mongolian  em- 
pire had  already,  fallen  to  pieces. 

For  the  channels  of  Christian  influence  upon  Lamaistic 
worship  search  must  be  made  within  Tibet  itself,  and  at 
any  rate  the  assumption  of  Hue62  can  not  be  ignored  that 
the  famous  reformer  of  Lamaism  Tsong-Kha-Pa  (1356- 
1418),  who  introduced  clerical  vestments  and  a  definitely 
prescribed  ritual,  had  been  under  the  influence  of  Christian 
missionaries,  even  though  we  possess  no  record  from  this 
period  of  a  Catholic  mission  to  Tibet.  But  central  Asia 
was  traversed  in  those  days  by  numerous  Christian  mis- 
sionaries, and  so  the  "man  from  the  west  with  the  long 
nose  and  eyes  gleaming  with  supernatural  fire,"6  with 
whom  Tsong-Kha-Pa  is  said  to  have  conversed,  may  have 
been  a  Christian  monk  who  found  his  way  there  not  from 
India  (for  then  something  more  definite  would  be  known 
of  him)  but  from  the  north  into  the  interior  of  Tibet. 

At  any  rate  since  the  Nestorians  of  the  seventh  cen- 
tury there  have  never  been  wanting  channels  through 
which  Christian  elements  of  worship  might  have  been  in- 
troduced into  Tibetan  Buddhism. 

61  See  also  Waddell,  p.  59;  Hackmann,  Buddhism  as  a  Religion,  pp.  74, 
75,  180. 

68  Hue,  Souvenirs,  II,  2d  ed.,  p.  106. 


CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  CHRISTIANITY  TO  BUDDHISM.     187 

In  conclusion  I  should  like  to  deny  one  possibility  which 
has  occasionally  been  suggested,  namely  that  the  Catholic 
ritual  may  not  have  influenced  the  Lamaistic,  but  vice 
versa  may  have  been  influenced  by  it.64  Lamaism  has 
never  possessed  the  requisite  strength  for  this.  The  side 
which  is  much  weaker  morally  and  intellectually  can  not 
urge  its  forms  of  life  upon  the  stronger. 

As  we  have  seen,  Christian  influences  upon  the  develop- 
ment of  Buddhism  are  limited  to  secondary  products  of  a 
late  day;  just  as  inversely  Buddhist  influences  upon  Chris- 
tianity may  be  pointed  out  only  in  non-essential  particu- 
lars and  from  times  in  which  the  doctrine  of  the  Christian 
faith  was  established  as  a  firm  system.  All  identities  and 
similarities  in  the  teachings  of  these  two  great  world- 
religions  have,  so  far  as  essential  matters  are  concerned, 
originated  independently  of  one  another,  and  therefore  are 
of  far  greater  significance  for  the  science  of  religion  than 
if  they  rested  upon  a  loan. 

RICHARD  GARBE. 

TUBINGEN,  GERMANY. 

"Waddell,  pp.  421-422:  "It  is  still  uncertain  how  much  of  the  Lamaist 
symbolism  might  have  been  borrowed  from  Roman  Catholicism,  or  vice  versa" ; 
Pischel,  Leben  und  Lehre  des  Buddha,  p.  124 :  "Without  doubt  much  has  trav- 
eled from  Lamaism  into  the  Catholic  church  since  even  Buddha  himself  as 
Josaphat  =  Bodhisattva  has  been  accepted  among  its  saints  in  the  Roman 
martyrology" — but  not  from  Lamaism!  We  have  distinct  indications  that 
Pischel  is  also  the  author  of  the  (anonymous)  article  on  Indian  religions  in 
Brockhaus's  Konversations-Lexikon,  I4th  ed.,  XVII,  where  we  read  on  page 
594 b:  "....so  that  the  service  of  Lamaism  closely  resembles  the  Catholic 
service  from  which  many  would  derive  it. ..  .But  the  reverse  path  of  the  loan 
is  equally  probable." 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY. 

INTRODUCTORY. 

PHYSICAL  science  seems  to  have  entered  into  a  new 
phase,  the  slogan  of  the  new  school  being  THE  PRIN- 
CIPLE OF  RELATIVITY.  In  some  quarters  the  current  modes 
of  thought  are  declared  antiquated,  and  the  promise  is 
made  that  the  old  truths  will  acquire  a  new  meaning. 
Physicists  speak  of  the  relativity  of  time  and  space,  and 
we  will  add  that  they  ought  as  well  speak  of  the  relativity 
of  things,  of  the  whole  actual  world  in  all  its  parts  and 
interrelations. 

Many  who  have  watched  the  origin  and  rise  of  the 
new  movement  are  startled  at  the  paradoxical  statements 
which  some  prominent  physicists  have  made,  and  it  is  re- 
markable that  the  most  materialistic  sciences,  mechanics 
and  physics,  seem  to  surround  us  with  a  mist  of  mysticism. 
The  old  self-contradictory  statements  of  the  Eleatic  school 
revive  in  a  modernized  form,  and  common  sense  is  baffled 
in  its  attempt  to  understand  how  the  same  thing  may  be 
longer  and  shorter  at  the  same  time,  how  a  clock  will 
strike  the  hour  later  or  sooner  according  to  the  point  of 
view  from  which  it  is  watched;  and  the  answer  of  this 
most  recent  conception  of  physics  to  the  question,  How  is 
this  all  possible?  is  based  on  the  principle  of  the  relativity 
of  time  and  space. 

The  man  who  started  this  movement  and  was  the  first 
to  formulate  it  in  concise  language  and  to  base  it  upon  close 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  189 

argument  was  Professor  Einstein,1  who  was  followed  by 
Lorentz,2  and  so  we  hear  often  of  the  Einstein-Lorentz 
theory.  The  strangest  thing  about  it  is  that  the  question 
is  seriously  debated  whether  or  not  this  theory  is  true,  and 
the  answer  is  expected  from  experiments;  while  in  our 
opinion  we  are  here  confronted  with  a  method,  and  the 
problem  is  simply  how  we  can  best  deal  with  certain  diffi- 
culties due  to  the  relativity  of  all  things.  These  difficulties 
have  originated  through  the  need  of  a  greater  exactness 
in  measurements,  but  the  underlying  truth — the  relativity 
of  all  things — is  not  a  question  of  fact,  but  a  recognition 
of  certain  complications  with  which  we  must  learn  to  deal. 

On  reading  recent  expositions  of  the  principle  of  rela- 
tivity the  man  of  good  education,  or  the  one  who  has  at- 
tended universities  without  being  a  specialist  in  either 
mathematics  or  physics,  feels  the  terra  firma  give  way 
under  his  feet,  and  when  he  finds  that  the  principle  of 
identity  seems  to  fail  in  his  comprehension  of  things,  a 
dizziness  comes  over  his  intellect  and  he  sinks  into  the 
bottomless  abyss  of  the  incomprehensibility  of  existence. 
A  general  earthquake  seems  to  quiver  through  his  mind. 
Everything  totters  around  him  and  he  stands  in  awe  at  the 
significance  of  the  new  thought.  Nor  is  there  any  one 
who  dares  to  contradict;  for  the  most  learned  arguments 
are  adduced,  the  mathematical  and  logical  conclusions  of 
which  bristle  with  formidable  formulas, — yea,  experiments 
are  made  to  prove  the  truth  of  the  relativity  of  time  and 
space. 

For  the  sake  of  convenience  we  will  speak  of  the  repre- 
sentatives of  this  new  conception  as  the  "relativity  physi- 
cists" in  contradistinction  to  the  old-fashioned  physicists 
of  the  old  school.  It  has  been  said  that  the  former  repre- 
sent more  the  mathematical  aspect  of  physics  while  the 

1Jahrbuch  der  Radio aktivit at  und  Elektronik,  1905-1908. 
*  H.  A.  Lorentz,  Theory  of  Electrons  (Teubner)   1910. 


THE  MONIST. 

latter  are  the  realistic  physicists  proper,  too  realistic  to 
understand  the  significance  of  the  new  truth. 

In  order  to  facilitate  a  comprehension  of  the  situation 
as  well  as  our  own  conception,  we  will  here  at  once  and 
dogmatically  state  that  the  relativity  physicists  are  per- 
fectly right;  what  they  claim  is  really  and  truly  a  matter 
of  course,  and  if  they  only  would  present  their  proposition 
without  dressing  up  their  theory  in  paradoxical  statements, 
nobody  would  in  the  least  hesitate  to  accept  the  new  view. 
But  as  soon  as  this  is  done  people  will  at  the  same  time 
find  out  that  the  new  view  is  not  novel.  Its  importance 
has  been  greatly  exaggerated,  for  the  principle  has  been 
tacitly  understood  in  the  correct  way  by  all  preceding  phys- 
icists who,  at  the  time  however,  ignored,  or  better  did  not 
enter  into,  the  problem,  because  they  had  other  more  press- 
ing work  on  hand.  Nor  is  it  unlikely  that  they  regarded 
this  problem  of  relativity  as  a  philosophical  question  which 
strictly  speaking  had  no  place  before  the  forum  of  physics. 

ON  THE  ABSOLUTE. 

Perhaps  the  easiest  way  of  elucidating  the  true  mean- 
ing of  the  relativity  of  time  and  space  will  be  by  setting 
forth  our  own  position  as  we  held  it  long  before  the  prin- 
ciple of  relativity  gained  prominence  or  had  even  been  men- 
tioned or  alluded  to. 

The  writer's  book  Fundamental  Problems  contains  the 
following  statement  under  "Definitions  and  Explanations" 
(first  edition,  page  254;  seecond  edition,  page  252)  : 

"Absolute  existence  (in  fact  everything  absolute)  is 
impossible.  Reality  is  properly  called  Wirklichkeit  in  Ger- 
man, derived  from  wirken,  to  take  effect.  Reality  is  not 
immovable  and  unchangeable  absoluteness,  but  the  effec- 
tiveness of  things  in  their  relations.  Reality  therefore  im- 
plies not  only  existence,  but  the  manifestation  of  existence 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY. 

also.    Existence  and  its  manifestation  are  not  two  different 
things;  both  are  one." 

Since  the  days  of  Heraclitus  it  has  been  a  trite  truism 
that  all  existence  is  in  a  flux.  There  is  no  rest  anywhere, 
and  actuality  consists  in  the  effects  which  these  changes 
exercise  upon  one  another  by  action  and  reaction.  Upon 
this  lack  of  stability,  resulting  from  a  universal  and  in- 
trinsic relativity,  Mr.  Spencer  bases  one  of  the  strongest, 
though  quite  untenable,  arguments  of  his  agnosticism.  He 
seems  to  expect  that  time,  space,  motion,  and  matter  are 
or  should  be  things-in-themselves,  and  forgets  that  they 
represent  relations,  i.  e.,  certain  features  of  reality.  We 
will  here  quote  his  exposition  of  the  unknowableness  of 
motion  in  space.  In  his  First  Principles  Spencer  says : 

"Here,  for  instance,  is  a  ship  which,  for  simplicity's  sake,  we 
will  suppose  to  be  anchored  at  the  equator  with  her  head  to  the 
west.  When  the  captain  walks  from  stem  to  stern,  in  what  direction 
does  he  move?  East,  is  the  obvious  answer, — an  answer  which  for 
the  moment  may  pass  without  criticism.  But  now  the  anchor  is 
heaved,  and  the  vessel  sails  to  the  west  with  a  velocity  equal  to 
that  at  which  the  captain  walks.  In  what  direction  does  he  now  move 
when  he  goes  from  stem  to  stern?  You  cannot  say  east,  for  the 
vessel  is  carrying  him  as  fast  towards  the  west  as  he  walks  to  the 
east ;  and  you  cannot  say  west  for  the  converse  reason.  In  respect  to 
surrounding  space  he  is  stationary ;  though  to  all  on  board  the  ship 
he  seems  to  be  moving.  But  now  are  we  quite  sure  of  this  conclusion  ? 
Is  he  really  stationary?  When  we  take  into  account  the  earth's 
motion  round  its  axis,  we  find  that  instead  of  being  stationary  he  is 
traveling  at  the  rate  of  1000  miles  per  hour  to  the  east;  so  that 
neither  the  perception  of  one  who  looks  at  him,  nor  the  inference 
of  one  who  allows  for  the  ship's  motion,  is  anything  like  the  truth. 
Nor  indeed,  on  further  consideration,  shall  we  find  this  revised  con- 
clusion to  be  much  better.  For  we  have  forgotten  to  allow  for  the 
earth's  motion  in  its  orbit.  This  being  some  68,000  miles  per  hour 
it  follows  that,  assuming  the  time  to  be  midday,  he  is  moving,  not  at 
the  rate  of  1000  miles  per  hour  to  the  east,  but  at  the  rate  of  67,000 
miles  per  hour  to  the  west.  Nay,  not  even  now  have  we  discovered 
the  true  rate  and  the  true  direction  of  his  movement.  With  the 


THE  MONIST. 

earth's  progress  in  its  orbit,  we  have  to  join  that  of  the  whole  solar 
system  towards  the  constellation  of  Hercules ;  and  when  we  do  this, 
we  perceive  that  he  is  moving  neither  east  nor  west,  but  in  a  line 
inclined  to  the  plane  of  the  ecliptic,  and  at  a  velocity  greater  or  less 
(according  to  the  time  of  the  year)  than  that  above  named.  To 
which  let  us  add,  that  were  the  dynamic  arrangements  of  our  sidereal 
system  fully  known  to  us,  we  should  probably  discover  the  direction 
and  rate  of  his  actual  movement  to  differ  considerably  even  from 
these.  How  illusive  are  our  ideas  of  motion,  is  thus  made  sufficiently 
manifest.  That  which  seems  moving  proves  to  be  stationary;  that 
which  seems  stationary  proves  to  be  moving;  while  that  which  we 
conclude  to  be  going  rapidly  in  one  direction,  turns  out  to  be  going 
much  more  rapidly  in  the  opposite  direction.  And  so  we  are  taught 
that  what  we  are  conscious  of  is  not  the  real  motion  of  any  object, 
either  in  its  rate  or  direction ;  but  merely  its  motion  as  measured 
from  an  assigned  position — either  the  position  we  ourselves  occupy 
or  some  other." 

The  same  argument  of  the  captain  walking  the  deck 
of  a  ship  was  made  before  Spencer,  though  mostly  it  was 
a  ball  rolling  on  deck;  Bradley  refers  to  it  as  well  known 
in  his  time,  1727,  and  the  same  story  has  been  repeated 
after  Spencer.  In  fact  it  is  one  of  the  arguments  of  the 
relativity  of  space  among  modern  relativity  physicists. 

The  principle  upon  which  the  representatives  of  the 
new  view  take  their  stand  is  a  consideration  of  actual  life. 
Things  are  in  a  flux,  and  this  is  an  undeniable  fact.  We 
must  bear  in  mind  that  the  way  of  making  knowledge  pos- 
sible at  all  in  the  flux  of  being  is  to  ignore  what  has  nothing 
to  do  with  the  problem  under  investigation.  Our  method 
is  based  upon  a  fiction  or,  if  you  please,  upon  an  artificial 
trick,  viz.,  to  ignore  complications  and  to  consider  a  certain 
thing  as  fixed;  but  there  are  cases  in  which  we  must  re- 
member that  we  ourselves  change  and  that  the  very  posi- 
tion we  assume  is  moving. 

This  trick  of  assuming  that  our  position  is  stable  is  easy 
enough  because  man  does  not  at  once  notice  that  there  is 
any  change;  but  all  things  are  in  a  flux  and  he  himself 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY. 

changes  unconsciously.  A  primitive  unsophisticated  man 
does  not  know  that  the  earth  on  which  he  stands  is  whirling 
around  itself  at  the  rate  of  1037  miles  an  hour,  on  the 
equator,  further  that  it  is  also  revolving  with  incredible 
speed  around  the  sun,  and  that  with  the  sun  it  is  proceeding 
in  a  spiral  motion  towards  one  of  the  constellations,  prob- 
ably the  constellation  Heracles,  around  an  unknown  center 
situated  somewhere  in  the  Milky  Way.  God  only  knows 
what  else  takes  place  and  what  kind  of  whirling  dances 
the  Milky  Way  performs.  The  savage  has  not  the  slightest 
idea  of  all  this,  and  so  it  is  easy  for  him  to  ignore  the  mo- 
tion of  which  he  unconsciously  partakes. 

If  man  really  were  aware  of  all  the  events  which  in- 
fluence him,  his  head  would  swim,  and  he  would  be  inca- 
pable of  thinking  any  sober  thought.  Fortunately  he  is 
concerned  solely  with  his  own  narrow  interests.  The  more 
man  in  the  further  growth  of  his  mind  becomes  familiar 
with  these  unnoticeable  events,  the  more  he  discovers  that 
for  any  particular  purpose  he  must  ignore  what  does  not 
belong  to  the  solution  of  the  special  problem  under  con- 
sideration. 

This  way  of  ignoring  what  does  not  concern  us  at  the 
time  is  an  artificial  process,  a  process  of  abstraction  and 
elimination,  of  cutting  off  all  disturbing  incidents,  and  in 
doing  so  the  philosophically  minded  scientist  will  become 
aware  of  the  fiction  of  arbitrarily  laying  down  a  point  of 
reference  which  is  treated  as  if  it  were  stable  while  in  fact, 
like  everything  else,  it  too  is  caught  in  the  maelstrom  of 
cosmic  existence. 

There  is  nothing  wrong  or  harmful  in  this  fiction;  on 
the  contrary  it  is  an  indispensable  part  of  our  method  of 
comprehending  things.  The  universe  is  too  complicated  to 
be  understood  or  viewed  at  a  glance,  and  knowledge,  sci- 
ence, cognition  as  well  as  all  mental  processes  become  pos- 
sible merely  by  concentration,  i.  e.,  by  selecting  a  point  of 


THE  MONIST. 

view  as  being  a  certain  fixed  location  from  which  we  ob- 
serve a  change,  an  event,  a  transformation,  in  order  to 
gain  a  comprehension  of  this  or  that  piece  of  existence  in 
contrast  to  others  of  the  same  or  of  a  different  kind.  Such 
is  the  nature  of  cognition,  and  this  artificial  trick  is  an 
essential  condition  of  observation. 

Knowledge  is  relative.  It  is  the  relation  between  sub- 
ject and  object,  the  thinker  and  the  thing,  and  this,  far 
from  being  objectionable,  is  only  the  universal  condition  of 
all  existence ;  for  all  existence  is  relative.  All  reality  is  the 
result  of  action  and  reaction;  it  is  a  forming  and  being 
formed  under  definite  conditions;  it  is  transformation. 
There  is  no  existence  in  and  by  itself.  Relativity  is  the 
principle  of  all  real  and  actual  being. 

TRICKS  OF  COGNITION. 

If  the  standpoint  of  an  observer  changes,  the  thing  ob- 
served will  naturally  change  too  in  its  relation  to  him. 
Formerly  physicists  were  in  the  habit  of  not  seriously  bear- 
ing in  mind  that  the  fixedness  of  their  standpoint  was  an 
assumption;  they  did  not  follow  this  principle  to  its  ulti- 
mate consequences.  For  their  special  problems  it  was  not 
necessary  to  do  so,  and  there  is  very  little  use  in  bearing 
it  constantly  in  mind.  The  difference  in  time  between  the 
moment  when  the  observer  looks  at  an  object  and  that  in 
which  the  rays  of  light  indispensable  for  observation  strike 
his  eye  is  too  inconsiderable  to  be  taken  into  account;  it  is 
a  negligible  quantity.  But  if  the  object  under  considera- 
tion is  at  such  an  enormous  distance  that  it  takes  the  rays 
of  light  thousands  of  years  to  reach  the  eye  of  the  astron- 
omer it  does  make  a  difference,  and  so  James  Bradley  was 
astonished  to  register  the  fact  that  the  fixed  stars  in  the  sky 
were  not  always  in  the  same  place  but  that  they  pendulated 
semi-annually  above  us  with  the  motion  of  the  earth  around 
the  sun.  The  direction  in  which  we  see  them  swings  from 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY. 

the  aphelion  to  the  perihelion,  and  a  closer  consideration 
of  the  facts  shows  that  the  rays  of  very  distant  stars  which 
we  catch  in  the  aphelion  are  not  caused  at  the  moment  when 
we  see  them  but  started  thousands  of  years  prior  to  the 
moment  in  which  they  strike  the  lens  of  the  astronomer's 
telescope,  and  so  the  transference  of  rays  of  light  from  the 
star  to  the  astronomer's  eye  at  this  enormous  distance  rep- 
resents a  relation  which  most  forcibly  drives  the  truth 
home  to  us  that  there  is  nothing  absolute. 

The  same  is  true  of  all  things.  The  object  before  us 
seems  to  stand  there  in  a  perfect  and  quiet  completeness, 
and  yet  the  changes  that  work  unnoticed  by  our  dull  senses 
are  constant,  continuous  and  rapid.  Heraclitus  used  to  say 
that  he  could  not  come  out  of  the  same  river  into  which  he 
had  stepped  a  moment  before,  because  the  water  was  al- 
ways rushing  by.  Never  is  a  drop  of  it  the  same,  and  this 
is  true  of  all  things,  even  of  ourselves.  The  observer  has 
to  exclude  from  his  methods  of  observation  the  fact  that 
he  himself,  his  senses  and  his  mind,  are  in  a  constant  flux. 

In  order  to  elucidate  the  significance  of  the  nature  of 
cognition  as  being  a  limitation  and  concentration  upon  one 
point  and  constructing  artificial  units,  the  writer  has  on 
former  occasions  used  the  analogy  of  the  kinematoscope, 
the  machine  which  produces  moving  pictures. 

In  order  to  make  any  picture  possible  we  need  a  lens, 
and  the  lens  focuses  the  rays  of  light  so  as  to  throw  rays 
from  the  same  spot  upon  one  and  the  same  place  on  the 
plane  where  the  picture  appears.  The  rays  of  light  which 
proceed  from  an  object  scatter  in  all  directions,  and  unless 
we  use  a  lens  to  concentrate  the  rays,  the  formation  of  a 
picture  of  the  object  would  remain  impossible.  Thus  the 
method  of  producing  a  picture  is  by  concentration. 

The  lens  produces  a  picture  by  focusing  rays  of  light, 
that  is  by  throwing  the  same  rays  upon  the  same  spot; 
but  it  would  also  be  possible  to  produce  a  picture  by  cutting 


196  THE   MONIST. 

off  the  redundant  rays  of  light  and  singling  out  one  or 
very  few  rays,  each  one  coming  from  each  of  the  several 
points  of  the  object.  Accordingly  we  can  photograph  ob- 
jects through  a  pinhole;  there  is  only  this  difference  that 
the  picture  is  weak  and  needs  long  exposure.  This  proves 
that  the  process  of  concentration  is  fundamentally  a  pro- 
cess of  abstraction,  of  leaving  out,  of  omitting  the  disturb- 
ing multiplicity  of  the  innumerable  facts  of  real  life  as 
represented  in  the  totality  of  objective  experience. 

The  kinematoscope  involves  not  only  the  static  form 
of  things,  their  spatial  expression,  the  juxtaposition  of 
parts,  but  it  also  adds  the  changes  that  are  taking  place  in 
time.  The  film  of  the  kinematoscope  consists  of  a  series  of 
pictures,  one  always  a  little  different  from  another,  and 
if  these  are  presented  in  rapid  succession  the  series  is  fused 
into  one  picture  in  which  the  succeeding  differences  appear 
as  motion.  This  is  accomplished  by  the  introduction  of  a 
little  winged  wheel  which  in  rapid  succession  covers  and 
uncovers  the  several  pictures.  If  we  would  take  this  little 
wheel  with  its  wings  out  of  the  kinematoscope,  and  if  other- 
wise the  pictures  on  the  film  would  succeed  one  another 
in  a  rapid  continuous  motion  without  this  artificial  separa- 
tion by  the  wings  of  the  wheel,  we  would  see  no  picture  at 
all  but  simply  have  a  blur  on  the  canvas.  In  order  to 
have  distinct  pictures  appear  on  the  canvas,  we  must  cut 
the  flux  of  motion  into  little  separate  moments  which  we 
may  allegorically  characterize  as  atoms  of  time. 

Reality  is  a  continuous  flux,  but  in  order  to  follow  it 
step  by  step  we  must  do  the  same  thing  that  the  mathema- 
tician does  with  his  differential  calculus.  In  the  calculus 
the  curve  is  cut  up  into  infinitesimal  lines,  which  in  con- 
tinuous succession  change  their  directions,  and  the  smaller 
we  conceive  these  lines  to  be,  the  less  is  the  mistake  made 
by  this  fiction,  if  they  are  treated  like  straight  lines. 

The  method  of  the  calculus,  based  upon  the  fiction  of 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY. 

substituting  for  a  continuous  curve  a  series  of  little  straight 
lines  constantly  changing  their  direction,  is  not  so  very 
different  from  the  method  of  cognition  in  general.  Nor 
is  there  anything  wrong  in  it,  only  we  must  remain  con- 
scious of  the  fiction.  In  a  similar  way  we  must  know  that 
existence  itself  is  a  continuous  system  of  relations,  or  in 
other  words,  that  relativity  is  the  principle  of  all  existence 
in  the  world  of  actual  life  as  well  as  in  the  domain  of 
thought.  We  must  cut  up  the  general  flux  according  to  the 

needs  of  our  investigation  and  lay  down  artificial  limits. 

*       *       * 

If  we  view  the  new  physics  under  this  aspect,  it  will 
lose  its  mystic  glamor  and  at  the  same  time  appear  intelli- 
gible. In  fact  we  shall  understand  that  the  principle  of 
relativity  is  a  matter  of  course,  and  if  we  cut  up  reality 
into  things,  as  if  they  were  things-in-themselves,  into  units 
or  atoms,  we  employ  a  trick  of  cognition  which  makes  it 
possible  to  focus  things  and  picture  them  distinctly  in  our 
mind. 

There  are  large  numbers  of  scientists  possessed  of  an 
odium  philosophicum  because  philosophy  means  to  them 
some  abstruse  metaphysical  system  of  thought  which  ig- 
nores the  natural  sciences  and,  spiderlike,  spins  a  world- 
conception  out  of  pure  thought  derived  from  the  thinker's 
subjectivity.  The  result  is  that  they  are  soon  perplexed  in 
their  own  science  by  philosophical  problems;  for  true  phi- 
losophy— the  philosophy  of  science — is  an  indispensable 
factor  of  cognition,  and  its  influence  extends  into  the  fabric 
of  all  scientific  labors.  Thus  it  happens  that  problems  of 
a  philosophical  character  arise  unexpectedly,  and  then  the 
information  given  by  nature  in  reply  to  experiments  is  apt 
to  be  misunderstood. 

If  the  reference  point  (R)  from  which  an  observer 
measures  is  in  motion  toward  RI,  and  the  object  observed 
(O)  also  possesses  a  motion  of  its  own,  we  are  confronted 


198  THE  MONIST. 

with  a  complicated  phenomenon.  If  R  moves  toward  O, 
the  object  measured  will  be  shorter  than  if  it  stands  still, 
and  it  will  be  longer  if  R  moves  with  O  in  the  same  direc- 
tion. We  have  only  to  forget,  after  the  fashion  of  the 
pragmatist,  that  there  is  an  ideal  of  objective  cognition, 
and  assume  that  all  there  is  about  size  or  the  objective 
measure  of  things  consists  in  the  result  of  our  measuring 
and  we  have  the  clue  to  the  paradoxes  of  the  physics  of 
relativity.  If  the  point  of  reference  is  not  stationary  and 
if  we  neglect  to  account  for  its  motion,  the  result  of  our 
measurement  is  necessarily  vitiated  thereby  as  much  as 
the  pragmatist's  philosophy  by  his  personal  equation. 

O 


R >- Ri 

Fig.  i. 

There  are  further  complications  of  measurement.  The 
time  needed  for  the  transmission  of  signals  must  also  be 
taken  into  consideration.  The  rays  of  light  travel  at  an 
enormous  velocity  but  the  distances  in  the  starry  heavens 
are  also  enormous  and  the  distance  between  O  and  R  is 
less  than  between  O  and  RI.  The  rays  which  were  sent 
out  from  O  at  the  moment  of  measurement  have  already 
passed  the  track  of  the  observer  at  R,  while  this  same  ob- 
server has  moved  on  to  RI,  and  there  he  catches  the  rays 
sent  out  from  O  in  its  position  at  O ;  in  the  meantime  how- 
ever the  object  O  has  in  its  turn  also  changed  its  place. 
From  RI  it  appears  at  O,  where  it  stood  while  the  observer 
was  stationed  at  R,  but  in  fact  it  stands  no  longer  at  O  but 
has  in  the  meantime  proceeded  on  its  own  path  whither- 
soever that  may  have  led  O,  backward  or  forward,  in  any 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  199 

other  direction  than  R,  possibly  in  the  same  direction  as  R. 
Such  phenomena  are  necessary  results  of  the  relativity  of 
existence,  and  we  must  bear  them  in  mind  when  confronted 
with  complicated  conditions  which  present  themselves,  for 
instance  in  astronomical  cases.  Here  the  mistakes  rising 
from  the  fiction  of  assuming  our  reference  point  to  be  stable 
are  considerable  enough  to  enforce  attention,  and  in  that 
case  we  shall  have  to  make  allowance  for  the  instability  of 
our  reference  point,  as  well  as  for  the  time  which  the  rays 
of  light  need  for  their  travel  through  space. 

That  was  exactly  Bradley's  case  as  set  forth  in  his 
essay  written  in  1727,  one  hundred  and  eighty-five  years 
ago,  and  thus  he  became  the  forerunner  of  the  relativity 
physicists.  To  state  it  in  other  terms,  Bradley  correctly 
solved  a  problem  which  in  our  days  led  to  the  formulation 
of  the  principle  of  relativity,  and  he  did  so  without  men- 
tioning this  theory,  yea  without  feeling  the  need  of  formu- 
lating it.  He  simply  took  it  for  granted  that  he  had  in  this 
case  to  consider  the  motion  of  the  earth  that  served  him 
as  a  reference  point — the  place  of  his  observations. 

COMSTOCK  ON  RELATIVITY. 

The  most  popular  and  at  the  same  time  the  most  exact 
characterization  of  the  principle  of  relativity  comes  from 
the  pen  of  Prof.  D.  F.  Comstock,  of  the  Massachusetts 
Institute  of  Technology.  It  appeared  in  Science  (Vol. 
XXXI,  1909,  p.  767),  and  we  quote  from  it  the  passages 
which  contain  the  statement  of  the  problem: 

Professor  Comstock  starts  with  the  following  two  pos- 
tulates : 

"The  uniform  translatory  motion  of  any  system  can  not  be  de- 
tected by  an  observer  traveling  with  the  system  and  making  obser- 
vations on  it  alone. 

"The  velocity  of  light  is  independent  of  the  relative  velocity 
of  the  source  of  light  and  observer." 


20O  THE  MONIST. 

The  main  passages  of  his  exposition  state  the  problem 
thus: 

"The  whole  principle  of  relativity  may  be  based  on  an  answer 
to  the  question:  When  are  two  events  which  happen  at  some  dis- 
tance from  each  other  to  be  considered  simultaneous?  The  answer, 
'When  they  happen  at  the  same  time/  only  shifts  the  problem.  The 
question  is,  how  can  we  make  two  events  happen  at  the  same  time 
when  there  is  a  considerable  distance  between  them. 

"Most  people  will,  I  think,  agree  that  one  of  the  very  best 
practical  and  simple  ways  would  be  to  send  a  signal  to  each  point 
from  a  point  half-way  between  them.  The  velocity  with  which 
signals  travel  through  space  is  of  course  the  characteristic  'space 
velocity/  the  velocity  of  light. 

"Two  clocks,  one  at  A  and  the  other  at  B,  can  therefore  be  set 
running  in  unison  by  means  of  a  light  signal  sent  to  each  from  a 
place  midway  between  them. 


2 


Fig.  2. 

"Now  suppose  both  clock  A  and  clock  B  are  on  a  kind  of 
sidewalk  or  platform  moving  uniformly  past  us  with  velocity  v. 
In  Fig.  2  (2)  is  the  moving  platform  and  (1)  is  the  fixed  one, 
on  which  we  consider  ourselves  placed.  Since  the  observer  on 
platform  (2)  is  moving  uniformly  he  can  have  no  reason  to  con- 
sider himself  moving  at  all,  and  he  will  use  just  the  method  we 
have  indicated  to  set  his  two  clocks  A  and  B  in  unison.  He  will 
send  a  light  flash  from  C,  the  point  midway  between  A  and  B, 
and  when  this  flash  reaches  the  two  clocks  he  will  start  them  with 
the  same  reading. 

"To  us  on  the  fixed  platform,  however,  it  will  of  course  be 
evident  that  the  clock  B  is  really  a  little  behind  clock  A,  for,  since 
the  whole  system  is  moving  in  the  direction  of  the  arrow,  light  will 
take  longer  to  go  from  C  to  B  than  from  C  to  A.  Thus  the  clock 
on  the  moving  platform  which  leads  the  other  will  be  behind  in  time. 

"Now  it  is  very  important  to  see  that  the  two  clocks  are  in  uni- 
son for  the  observer  moving  with  them  (in  the  only  sense  in  which 
the  word  'unison'  has  any  meaning  for  him),  for  if  we  adopt  the  first 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  2OI 

postulate  of  relativity,  there  is  no  way  in  which  he  can  know  that  he 
is  moving.  In  other  words,  he  has  just  as  much  fundamental  right 
to  consider  himself  stationary  as  we  have  to  consider  ourselves  sta- 
tionary, and  therefore  just  as  much  right  to  apply  the  midway  signal 
method  to  set  his  clocks  in  unison  as  we  have  in  the  setting  of  our 
'stationary  clocks.'  'Stationary/  is,  therefore,  a  relative  term  and 
anything  which  we  can  say  about  the  moving  system  dependent  on 
its  motion,  can  with  absolutely  equal  right  be  said  by  the  moving 
observer  about  our  system. 

"We  are,  therefore,  forced  to  the  conclusion  that,  unless  we 
discard  one  of  the  two  relativity  postulates,  the  simultaneity  of  two 
distant  events  means  a  different  thing  to  two  different  observers  if 
they  are  moving  with  respect  to  each  other." 

We  quote  further : 

"It  must  be  emphasized  that,  because  of  the  first  fundamental 
postulate,  there  is  no  universal  standard  to  be  applied  in  settling  such 
a  difference  of  opinion.  Neither  the  standpoint  of  the  'moving'  ob- 
server nor  our  standpoint  is  wrong.  The  two  merely  represent  two 
different  sides  of  reality.  Any  one  could  ask:  What  is  the  'true' 
length  of  a  metal  rod?  Two  observers  working  at  different  tem- 
peratures come  to  different  conclusions  as  to  the  'true  length.'  Both 
are  right.  It  depends  on  what  is  meant  by  'true.'  Again,  asking 
a  question  which  might  have  been  asked  centuries  ago,  is  a  man 
walking  toward  the  stern  of  an  eastbound  ship  really  moving  west? 
We  must  answer  'That  depends'  and  we  must  have  knowledge  of  the 
questioner's  view-point  before  we  can  answer  yes  or  no." 

The  question  of  the  man  walking  on  a  ship  not  only 
"might  have  been  asked  centuries  ago,"  but  it  has  been 
asked  centuries  ago.  Our  forebears  were  more  conscious 
of  the  relativity  of  existence  than  the  relativity  physicists 
credit  them. 

Professor  Comstock  continues: 

"It  must  be  remembered  that  the  results  of  the  principle  of 
relativity  are  as  true  and  no  truer  than  its  postulates.  If  future 
experience  bears  out  these  postulates  then  the  length  of  the  body, 
even  of  a  geometrical  line,  in  fact  the  very  meaning  of  'length,' 
depends  on  the  point  of  view,  that  is,  on  the  relative  motion  of  the 
observer  and  the  object  measured." 


2O2  THE  MONIST. 

Professor  Comstock's  verdict  of  the  case  is  summarized 
in  this  paragraph: 

"The  results  of  the  principle  for  uniform  translation  are  simply 
as  true  as  its  two  postulates.  If  either  of  these  postulates  be  proved 
false  in  the  future,  then  the  structure  erected  can  not  be  true  in  its 
present  form.  The  question  is,  therefore,  an  experimental  one." 

Here  we  demur.  We  claim  that  the  question  is  not  ex- 
perimental but  belongs  to  the  department  of  a  priori  rea- 
soning. 

Professor  Comstock  does  not  enter  into  questions  of 
mass  connected  with  the  principle  of  relativity  but  is  satis- 
fied with  this  comment : 

"The  apparent  transverse  mass  is,  I  think,  best  derived  by  Lewis 
and  Tolman,3  in  their  excellent  paper  on  the  principle  of  relativity, 
and  the  relation  between  transverse  and  longitudinal  mass  is  shown 
in  the  most  direct  and  simple  way  by  Bumstead4  making  use  of  the 
torsion  pendulum.  Any  one  interested  in  the  subject  should  read 
these  two  papers." 

THE  A   PRIORI. 

It  is  characteristic  of  modern  science  to  denounce  the 
principle  of  the  a  priori  and  to  extol  experiment  and  expe- 
rience. Now  it  is  true  that  experience  and  experiment  are 
indispensable  factors  in  science,  and  in  all  the  specialties 
of  science.  Jn  experience  and  experiments  we  deal  with 
the  facts  presented  to  us  by  nature;  but  the  method  of 
reasoning  is  not  a  thing  which  is  derived  from  sense  ex- 
perience. 

The  method  of  reasoning  is,  as  Kant  truly  said,  a  priori 
and,  let  us  add,  the  a  priori  is  nothing  mystical  or  mysteri- 
ous; it  is  simply  the  result  of  pure  thought  or  reflection 
from  which  the  data  of  the  senses  have  been  excluded. 
Pure  thought  (or  better,  purely  formal  thought)  is  a  men- 
tal construction,  or,  if  you  prefer,  a  fiction.  We  omit  every- 

9  Phil.  Mag.,  18,  510-523,  1909. 

*  Am.  Jour,  of  Science,  26,  pp.  493-508,  1909. 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  2O3 

thing  concrete  and  thus  we  retain  a  field  of  abstract  possi- 
bilities. Elsewhere  we  have  called  it  a  field  of  anyness.5 
Obliterating  in  our  mind  all  particularity  we  retain  noth- 
ing concrete  and  in  this  field  of  nothingness  we  build  up 
pure  relations.  From  this  domain  all  real  things,  com- 
prising everything  which  we  subsume  under  the  categories 
of  matter  and  energy,  has  been  excluded.  But  these  pure 
relations,  i.  e.,  pure  forms  which  are  non-material  con- 
structions lacking  all  concrete  qualities  such  as  all  real 
things  possess,  serve  us  as  models  for  the  relations  of  any 
possible  purely  mental  or  actual  existence.  Our  doings  in 
this  field  of  abstraction  consist  in  the  fiction  of  pure  lines, 
pure  numbers,  pure  motion,  pure  ideas  and  their  inter- 
relations such  as  genera  and  species,  and  thus  we  are  ca- 
pable of  building  up  a  world  of  purely  formal  or  relational 
thought,  the  totality  of  which  in  space  is  called  geometry, 
and  in  the  domain  of  numbers  which  originate  by  counting 
a  series  of  single  units,  arithmetic,  etc.  In  the  domain  of 
pure  thought,  consisting  of  genera  and  species,  we  call  the 
laws  that  govern  their  relations  logic,  and  the  law  of  trans- 
formation, of  which  the  positive  aspect  is  properly  called 
causality,  and  its  negative  counterpart  the  law  of  conser- 
vation of  matter  and  energy,  has  been  called  by  Kant  pure 
natural  science. 

All  systems  of  mental  constructions  have  the  advantage 
of  picturing  in  our  mind  any  possible  configuration  of  rela- 
tivity, and  in  this  sense  pure  thought  (Kant's  a  priori)  is 
a  field  of  anyness.  It  can  be  applied  to  any  fact  or  set  of 
facts  of  existence,  actual  or  fictitious,  and  these  systems 
of  mental  constructions  therefore  furnish  us  with  the  key 
to  determine  the  relations  of  real  nature.  They  render 
possible  the  systematization  of  sense  impressions  and  thus 

BSee  Philosophy  of  Form,  the  chapter  on  "The  Foundation  of  Mathe- 
matics and  Logic,"  pp.  7-10.  For  further  details  see  also  the  chapter  "Form 
and  Formal  Thought"  in  the  author's  Fundamental  Problems,  pp.  26-60. 


2O4  THE  MONIST. 

these  systems  of  pure  thought  in  the  field  of  anyness  are 
the  methods  of  scientific  operation. 

Let  us  not  therefore  speak  contemptuously  of  the  a 
priori,  or  denounce  apriorism  as  something  medieval  and 
elusive,  for  even  here  in  the  attempt  at  establishing  the 
principle  of  relativity  in  time  and  space,  the  arguments  of 
the  physicists  are  absolutely  aprioristic.  There  is  not  one 
of  these  so-called  experiments,  invented  to  prove  the  rela- 
tivity of  time  and  space,  which  does  not  ultimately  resolve 
itself  into  a  machine  that  renders  visible  aprioristic  con- 
siderations. 

The  ultimate  arguments  in  all  the  experiments  made 
to  prove  the  relativity  of  time  and  space  move  in  a  domain 
of  purely  formal  thought,  and  the  force  of  them  is  ulti- 
mately of  the  same  kind  as  the  Q.  E.  D.  of  Euclidean  theo- 
rems. We  think  here  mainly  of  such  propositions  as  locate 
an  observer  on  the  sun  and  another  on  the  earth.  Their 
clocks  actually  agree,  but  when  compared  they  are  found 
to  differ.  About  eight  minutes  have  elapsed  when  the 
observer  on  earth  registers  the  time  as  the  rays  of  the  sun 
reach  the  earth,  and  vice  versa  when  the  clock  on  earth 
is  observed  as  the  rays  from  the  earth  strike  the  sun.  The 
imitation  of  the  same  conditions  for  the  sake  of  comparing 
the  registration  of  two  moving  systems  in  an  actual  ex- 
periment amounts  to  nothing  more  than  the  pencil  draw- 
ings of  a  Euclidean  or  logical  figure  in  which  the  a  priori 
reasoning  is  visibly  presented  as  a  demonstratio  ad  oculos. 
The  argument  remains  in  either  case  one  of  pure  thought. 

The  photograph  of  such  an  apparatus  built  for  the  pur- 
pose of  making  an  experiment  in  the  relativity  of  time  and 
space  to  show  the  difference  between  a  solar  clock  and  a 
terrestrial  clock  may  be  found  in  the  article  of  Emil  Cohn 
of  Strassburg,  "Physikalisches  iiber  Raum  und  Zeit"  in 
Himmel  und  Erde,  Vol.  XXIII.  To  be  sure  the  instru- 
ment does  not  fulfil  the  conditions  either  of  distance  or  of 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  2O5 

the  velocity  of  the  transference  of  the  signal,  "but,"  says 
Professor  Cohn,  "that  is  of  secondary  importance." 

There  are  two  motions  both  constant  and  both  stand- 
ing in  a  definite  proportion.  The  sun  with  its  clocks  has 
been  made  to  stand  still.  The  earth  with  its  two  clocks 
moves,  and  there  is  an  arrangement  by  which  to  represent 
the  transference  of  signals.  The  main  thing  is  that  "their 
velocities  stand  in  definite  proportions  and  all  that  concerns 
us  are  these  proportions.  That  we  have  here  replaced  the 
enormous  velocity  of  light  by  a  velocity  of  a  few  centi- 
meters per  seecond  is  unessential.  It  is  essential,  however, 
that  the  velocity  of  the  earth  is  three-fourths  the  velocity 
of  light,  while  the  real  ratio  is  i :  10,000." 

Newton's  laws  are  a  priori,  and  Newton  proves  that 
these  laws  hold  good  in,  and  are  serviceable  as,  interpreta- 
tions of  the  actual  world  of  fact.  The  empiricist  ought  to 
rebel  against  Newton's  laws,  because  they  never  have  been 
nor  ever  can  be  proved  by  either  experience  or  experiment. 
Whoever  saw  a  body  moving  in  a  straight  line?  and  has 
Newton  (from  the  standpoint  of  the  empiricist)  any  right 
at  all  to  make  such  sweeping  statements  of  movements 
which  have  never  occurred  in  the  experience  of  anybody? 

The  most  general  principle  at  the  bottom  of  scientific 
work  is  perhaps  the  so-called  law  of  the  conservation  of 
matter  and  energy,  and  even  this  law  is  based  on  purely 
a  priori  arguments. 

Incidentally  we  will  say  that  the  law  does  not  hold 
good  if  we  restrict  the  notion  of  matter  to  matter  in  the 
sense  of  the  physicist  which  is  mass,  i.  e.,  to  concrete  par- 
ticles of  existence  that  are  extended  and  possess  weight. 
It  holds  good  only  if  we  understand  by  matter  the  substance 
of  being,  its  objective  reality.  We  had  better  therefore 
speak  of  the  conservation  not  of  matter  but  of  substance, 
for  gross  matter,  consisting  of  the  chemical  elements,  is 
constantly  being  produced  before  our  eyes  in  the  starry 


2O6  THE  MONIST. 

heavens  where  the  astronomers  can  watch  the  process 
through  their  telescopes.  In  the  nebulas  we  see  now  the 
commotion  of  whirls  with  which  gradually  first  the  lighter 
and  then  the  heavier  chemical  elements  are  being  manu- 
factured out  of  the  original  world-substance  which  we 
assume  to  be  the  same  as  the  luminiferous  ether. 

Therefore  we  may  surrender  the  law  of  conservation 
of  gross  matter,  but  we  still  hold  to  the  conception  that 
there  is  a  conservation  of  stuff  or  substance,  and  the  same 
is  true  of  energy.  There  may  be  energy  in  the  shape  of 
a  stress  incorporated  in  the  same  wonderful  world  stuff, 
the  ether,  and  this  stress  may  be  set  free  and  become  actual 
motion  or  kinetic  energy,  by  some  cause  which  creates 
those  whirls  that  start  the  formation  of  nebulas. 

And  what  proves  the  law  of  this  conservation  of  sub- 
stance and  energy?  It  is  the  necessity  of  a  priori  thought 
which  compels  us  to  assume  the  principle  that  nothing 
originates  from  nothing  and  nothing  disappears  into  noth- 
ing, which  thought  rests  ultimately  on  the  idea  that  all 
processes  of  existence  are  transformations.  Everything 
that  originates  is  formed  by  combination  from  something 
that  existed  before. 

It  has  been  maintained  that  the  principle  of  relativity 
must  be  proved  experimentally,  but  this  is  a  mistake.  Real- 
ity is  everywhere  a  system  of  interrelations,  yea  every 
single  concrete  thing,  every  phenomenon,  every  piece  of 
existence  is  a  bundle  of  relations.  It  can  be  analyzed  into 
its  elements,  which  are  actions  and  reactions;  and  that  is 
all  that  reality  means.  Space  as  well  as  time  are  merely 
the  measures,  the  former  of  arrangement  or  position,  the 
latter  of  succession.  Space  denotes  the  interrelation  of 
parts  constituting  figures  or  shapes  affording  a  mode  of 
determining  direction  and  distance.  Time  measures  the 
duration  of  events  which  is  done  by  counting  uniform 
cyclical  motions  or  parts  thereof.  And  so  we  must  grant 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  2O7 

that  the  relativity  of  time  and  space,  as  well  as  of  all  real 
things  is  a  universal  and  inalienable  condition  of  all  exist- 
ence. We  can  not  think  of  any  actuality  which  would  not 
be  dominated  by  relativity;  which  means  we  must  regard 
the  principle  of  relativity  as  an  a  priori  postulate. 

The  principle  of  relativity  is  not  established  by  expe- 
rience but  is  ultimately  based  upon  reflection  and  pure 
ratiocination.  It  belongs  to  the  category  of  purely  formal 
thought  as  much  as  all  arithmetical  and  geometrical  propo- 
sitions. 

If  any  proposition  of  purely  formal  thought,  such  as 
2X2  =  4,  does  not  hold  good  in  our  experience,  we  doubt 
the  correctness  of  our  counting  or  measuring,  but  we  do 
not  doubt  our  a  priori  proposition.  We  revise  our  obser- 
vation, not  our  logic,  our  arithmetic,  our  mathematics ;  and 
suppose  our  observation  proves  true,  suppose  that  2X2 
rabbits  shut  up  in  a  cage  are  on  recounting  their  number 
found  to  be  more  than  four,  say  six  or  ten  or  any  higher 
amount,  we  do  not  upset  our  arithmetic  or  any  of  our 
purely  formal  propositions,  but  seek  the  cause  of  the  ir- 
regularity in  the  objects,  in  the  things  or  animals  counted. 
In  that  case  we  are  positive  that  some  transformation  of 
the  concrete  material  has  set  in  which  adds  to  the  number 
to  be  expected  according  to  arithmetical  law. 

If  the  reference  point  (R)  belongs  to  the  same  system 
of  motion  as  the  object  observed  (O),  our  measurement 
will  be  correct  and  indicate  the  size  of  the  object  ade- 
quately. But  if  R  moves  in  a  direction  and  with  a  velocity 
of  its  own,  different  from  O,  the  measurement  will  not  be 
adequate;  it  will  be  warped  in  an  exact  proportion  to  the 
motion  of  R,  and  this  rule  holds  good  in  the  same  way  as 
all  mathematical,  logical  and  generally  purely  formal  theo- 
rems. 

The  reliability  of  purely  formal  truths  is  not  merely 
theoretical,  but  finds  its  application  in  practical  life,  in  the 


2O8  THE   MONIST. 

objective  world  of  matter  and  motion,  and  can  be  verified 
by  experience  and  experiment.  And  this  is  true  also  of 
the  relativity  of  time  and  space. 

If  for  instance  a  photographer  takes  the  picture  of  a 
rapid  express  train  in  motion  with  a  camera  provided 
with  a  curtain  shutter,  the  wheels  will  not  be  round  but 
oval  in  the  photograph,  and  the  relativity  photographer 
who  identifies  the  picture  with  the  thing,  in  the  same  way 
as  the  relativity  physicist  identifies  the  result  of  measur- 
ing with  the  objective  size  of  the  object  measured,  will 
claim  that  in  proportion  to  the  velocity  of  the  train  times 
the  inverse  proportion  of  the  velocity  of  the  slit  in  the 
curtain  of  the  shutter,  the  wheels  will  increase  their  hori- 
zontal diameters  and  become  that  much  more  oval.  Yea 
they  will  insist  that  the  very  same  wheel  will  be  at  the 
same  time  in  one  camera,  only  a  little  more,  in  another 
one  much  more  oval  according  to  the  quickness  with  which 
the  slit  of  the  curtain  passes  over  the  sensitive  plate. 

The  relativity  photographer  will  claim  that  the  wheels 
in  motion  are  oval  while  common  mortals  think  that  they 
only  appear  oval  in  the  photograph. 

Photographs  do  not  lie;  they  show  the  objects  photo- 
graphed without  any  personal  equation  on  the  part  of  the 
photographer;  their  objectivity  and  impartiality  can  not 
be  doubted,  and  here  we  see  the  wheels  oval.  They  are 
oval,  and  their  ovality,  viz.,  their  deviation  from  true  cir- 
cles, depends  on  the  velocity  of  certain  motions.  An  en- 
thusiast for  the  principle  of  relativity  can  justly  claim  that 
every  photograph  of  a  rapid  train  which  shows  the  oval 
form  of  the  wheels  is  a  successful  experiment  in  the  demon- 
stration of  the  relativity  of  figure  in  space. 

The  truth  of  the  principle  of  relativity  in  the  domain 
of  photography  can  be  explained  by  a  priori  considerations. 
It  is  a  matter  of  course,  and  if  we  argue  the  subject  in  our 
mind  in  pure  reflection,  we  find  out  what  we  must  expect, 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  2OQ 

and  if  finally  we  make  the  experiment,  the  principle  proves 
true. 

In  the  same  way  all  the  experiments  made  by  machin- 
ery so  constructed  as  to  represent  terrestrial  and  solar 
clocks  or  yard  sticks,  and  to  point  out  the  unavoidable  dif- 
ference of  measurements  in  both  time  and  size  resultant 
from  their  respective  motions  of  the  earth  and  the  sun  as 
well  as  the  time  it  takes  to  transmit  signals,  are  not  experi- 
ments in  the  physicist's  sense  but  expositions  and  demon- 
strations of  purely  formal  truths  which  belong  to  the  cat- 
egory of  mathematics. 

If  the  principle  of  relativity  does  not  hold  good  in  any 
domain  of  actual  life,  we  must  seek  the  cause  in  the  mate- 
rial used  and  not  in  the  principle  of  relativity.  In  other 
words  we  would  be  confronted  with  a  purely  physical  prob- 
lem which  demands  a  physical  solution,  and  this  seems  to 
be  the  case  of  the  Fizeau  experiment. 

Prof.  Emil  Cohn,  of  Strassburg,6  says: 

"It  is  strange  that  the  relativity  principle  of  mechanics  does  not 
hold  good  in  radiation — in  radiation  and  therewith  in  electrodynamics, 
for  that  the  spread  of  radiation  is  an  electrical  process  we  may  con- 
sider since  Heinrich  Hertz  as  an  assured  matter  of  experience.  The 
decisive  experiment  which  has  been  made  by  Fizeau  is  this:  In  a 
liquid,  flowing  with  a  uniform  velocity,  light  is  to  be  propagated  in 
the  direction  of  the  current.  According  to  the  relativity  principle 
an  observer  drifting  in  the  current  should  find  the  velocity  of  propa- 
gation to  be  the  same  as  if  the  liquid  were  at  rest,  and  an  outside 
observer  should  find  the  velocity  of  the  light  augmented  by  the  full 
velocity  of  the  current  in  the  liquid.  (Think,  e.  g.,  of  the  ball 
rolling  on  the  deck  of  a  ship  in  motion.)  But  such  is  not  the  case. 
There  is  added  only  a  certain  portion,  viz.,  the  index  of  refraction." 

The  very  result  of  the  experiment  proves  that  one  of 
the  determinant  factors  is  the  physical  property  of  the 
fluid. 

When  the  principle  of  relativity  is  applied  to  positive 

6  Loc.  cit.,  p.  7. 


2IO  THE  MONIST. 

facts  we  reach  slippery  ground,  on  which  we  must  be  on 
our  guard  to  avoid  mystification,  for  it  would  seem  as  if 
the  law  of  the  conservation  of  matter  and  energy  were 
upset  and  all  objectivity  of  scientific  truth  were  lost.  Ex- 
periments have  been  made  to  prove  the  principle  of  rela- 
tivity with  the  result  that  Hupka  and  Bucherer,7  the  former 
with  cathode  rays,  the  latter  with  radium  rays,  demon- 
strate that  mass  increases  with  velocity  as  the  relativity 
principle  demands.  Kaufmann,  however,  comes  to  the 
conclusion  that  there  is  an  increase  of  mass  but  not  as 
ought  to  be  expected  according  to  the  principle  of  relativ- 
ity, while  Michelson  and  Morley  demonstrate  with  great 
exactness  that  in  spite  of  the  motion  of  the  earth  the  trans- 
mission of  light  is  not  changed  at  all,  not  within  one  hun- 
dred millionth  of  its  proportion  nor  even  a  fraction  thereof. 
It  would  lead  us  too  far  to  discuss  the  experiments 
made  to  apply  the  principle  of  relativity  to  physics  and 
electrodynamics;  we  will  only  mention  that  (as  a  priori 
might  be  expected)  they  tend  to  corroborate  its  applica- 
bility in  these  domains. 

ON    ABSOLUTE   MOTION. 

Dr.  Philipp  Frank  in  his  discussion  "Does  Absolute 
Motion  Exist?"8  declares  that  motion  in  physics  always 
means  "motion  with  reference  to  some  definite  body,"  and 
he  recognizes  that  "this  question  is  a  philosophical  one9 
but  it  is  certainly  not  a  physical  question/'  The  answer 
is  the  first  Newtonian  law,  viz.,  "A  body  not  affected  by 
an  exterior  force  moves  in  a  straight  line  with  a  constant 

7  A.  H.  Bucherer,  "Die  experimentelle  Bestatigung  des  Relativitatsprin- 
zips"  in  Annalen  der  Physik,  XXVIII,  p.   513;   "Messungen  an  Becquerel- 
strahlen"  in  Physikalische  Zeitschrift,  IX,  pp.  755-760. 

8  "Gibt  es  eine  absolute  Bewegung  ?"    Lecture  delivered  December  4, 1909, 
at  the  University  of  Vienna  before  the  Philosophical  Society.    Wissenschaft- 
liche  Beilage,  1910. 

9  Dr.  Frank  adds  here :  "Perhaps  the  psychologist  would  call  it  a  psycho- 
logical one,"  but  this  would  be  a  mistake.     Psychology  has  nothing  to  do 
with  the  subject. 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  211 

velocity  which  of  course  may  be  zero.10  This  is  called  the 
law  of  inertia." 

If  another  force  affects  the  moving  body  it  is  subject  to 
the  second  law,  the  law  of  the  parallelogram  of  forces,  ac- 
cording to  which  the  body  will  move  along  the  diagonal  of 
the  two  forces. 

The  following  extracts  translated  from  Dr.  Frank's 
essay  on  absolute  motion  will  prove  instructive: 

"The  system  of  the  fixed  stars  constitutes  a  fundamental  body. 
Even  in  shooting  a  cannon  ball  towards  the  south  we  see  no  devia- 
tion from  the  law  of  inertia  if  we  consider  it  with  reference  to  the 
fixed  stars.  The  ball  remains  in  the  same  plane ;  but  this  plane  does 
not  retain  the  same  relative  position  to  the  meridian  of  the  earth, 
wherefore,  of  course,  with  reference  to  the  earth  the  law  of  inertia 
is  violated.  On  the  whole  it  is  evident  that  we  really  recover  all  the 
observed  motor  phenomena  when  we  refer  Newton's  laws  of  motion 
to  the  fixed  stars.  Not  until  they  are  referred  to  the  fixed  stars  do 
these  laws  acquire  an  exact  sense  which  makes  it  possible  to  apply 
them  to  concrete  conditions. 

"We  shall  call  those  motions  which  are  referred  to  a  fundamental 
body  'true  movements'  and  those  related  to  any  other  body  of  ref- 
erence 'apparent  movements.'  For  instance  the  immobility  of  my 
chair  is  only  apparent,  for  when  referred  to  the  fixed  stars  it  is  in 
motion. 

"We  now  ask  whether  there  are  any  other  fundamental  bodies 
aside  from  the  system  of  the  fixed  stars.  Obviously  not  any  body 
revolving  in  an  opposite  direction  to  the  fixed  stars  can  be  such  a 
fundamental  body,  for  considered  with  reference  to  such  a  body  all 
rectilinear  movements  are  curved.  Therefore  the  law  of  inertia 
could  not  hold  with  reference  to  the  body  in  question  if  it  is  valid 
with  reference  to  the  fixed  stars.  Then  too  a  fundamental  body  can 
possess  no  acceleration  with  reference  to  the  fixed  stars,  because 
otherwise  there  would  be  no  uniformity  of  the  motion  of  inertia  with 
reference  to  it.  However,  these  conditions  are  not  only  necessary 
but  they  are  sufficient  to  characterize  a  fundamental  body.  All  bodies 
moving  uniformly  and  in  a  straight  line  with  reference  to  the  fixed 
stars  will  also  be  fundamental  bodies  inasmuch  as  rectilinearity  and 

10 The  original  reads  thus:  "Corpus  omne  perseverare  in  statu  suo  quies- 
cendi  vel  movendi  uniformiter  in  directum  nisi  quatenus  a  viribus  impressis 
cogitur  statum  ilium  mutare." 


212  THE  MONIST. 

uniformity  continue  to  hold  for  them,  as  do  likewise  the  supple- 
mentary velocities  determined  by  the  second  law.  Accordingly  New- 
ton's laws  do  not  indicate  one  single  fundamental  body,  but  an  in- 
finite number  moving  in  opposite  directions  with  a  uniform  and 
rectilinear  motion. 

"Hence  we  may  well  speak  of  'true'  in  contrast  to  apparent 
rotary  motion;  for  all  bodies  revolving  with  reference  to  a  funda- 
mental body  revolve  with  reference  to  all  other  bodies.  The  same 
is  true  of  true  acceleration  because  an  acceleration  with  respect  to 
a  fundamental  body  is  also  acceleration  (i.  e.,  change  of  velocity) 
with  respect  to  all  the  rest.  On  the  other  hand,  there  is  no  sense 
in  speaking  of  'true'  uniform  rectilinear  motion ;  for  if  a  body  pos- 
sesses a  uniform  velocity  with  respect  to  the  fixed  stars,  it  is  itself  a 
fundamental  body  possessing  of  course  with  respect  to  itself  a 
velocity  of  zero ;  it  is  at  rest. 

"Accordingly  there  is  true  acceleration,  but  not  true  velocity. 
From  this  is  easily  derived  a  proposition  established  by  Newton 
which  is  called  the  principle  of  relativity  of  mechanics,  namely  that 
a  uniform  rectilinear  movement  of  the  system  as  a  whole  makes  no 
change  in  the  processes  within  the  system ;  that  is  to  say,  we  can  not 
tell  from  the  processes  within  the  system  what  velocity  the  uniform 
rectilinear  movement  possesses  with  reference  to  the  fixed  stars. 
On  the  other  hand,  the  rotary  motion  of  a  system  has  indeed  an  in- 
fluence on  the  processes  within  the  system,  as  for  instance  in  the 
phenomena  of  centrifugal  force ;  thus  the  earth  has  become  flattened 
at  its  poles  because  of  its  rotation,  or  if  I  revolve  a  dish  full  of  water 
the  water  will  rise  at  the  sides." 

ABSOLUTE  SPACE. 

If  we  make  measurements  of  motions  which  are  lim- 
ited to  terrestrial  conditions,  the  earth  is  and  must  be  the 
system  which,  though  not  absolute,  must  for  the  nonce  be 
so  considered,  and  in  that  case  the  earth  is  called  the  funda- 
mental or  inertial  body,  of  our  measurements.  But  in 
many  purely  terrestrial  motions  we  observe  in  very  precise 
and  exact  measurements,  deviations  which  compel  us  to 
seek  for  another  fundamental  body. 

This  happens  in  the  case  of  the  Foucault  pendulum  ex- 
periments and  may  also  be  observed  in  a  cannon  ball  which 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  213 

if  shot  south  along  the  meridian  will  at  a  great  distance 
show  a  deviation  toward  the  west.  Such  experiments 
point  out  that  the  entire  system  of  the  fixed  stars  ought 
to  be  regarded  as  the  fundamental  body  which  thus  would 
represent  to  us  absolute  space.  I  say  here  on  purpose 
"represent  to  us/'  not  "be,"  because  we  are  most  probably 
in  the  same  predicament  as  persons  moving  in  a  train  to 
whom  the  train  and  its  interrelations,  so  long  as  the  train 
does  not  move  in  a  curve,  represent  the  fundamental  body 
or  absolute  space,  viz.,  the  ultimate  system  of  reference. 

It  stands  to  reason  that  bodies  in  translation  (in  which 
the  entire  system  as  a  whole  moves  in  the  same  direction 
with  the  same  velocity  and  without  any  internal  change 
even  of  its  smallest  particles)  behave  as  if  they  were  at 
rest,  and  so  the  motion  of  a  straight  line  cannot  be  observed 
so  long  as  the  observer  remains  limited  to  his  own  system. 
Every  deviation  from  a  straight  line,  however,  implies  a 
retardation  on  the  inner  side  of  the  curve,  or,  what  means 
the  same,  an  acceleration  on  the  outside  of  the  curved  path 
of  motion.  Accordingly  all  rotations  bear  witness  to  the 
character  of  their  motion  as  appears  in  the  Foucault  pen- 
dulum experiment  and  in  the  flattening  of  the  earth  at  the 
poles.  Since  further  the  idea  of  a  rectilinear  motion  is  a 
mere  a  priori  postulate  which  can  never  be  realized  in 
actual  nature,  we  see  that  every  motion  that  takes  place 
anywhere  is  affected  by  the  totality  of  the  universe.  We 
must  assume  that  its  existence  (the  existence  indeed  of 
every  particular  thing  or  the  recurrence  of  any  event)  must 
be  understood  to  be  a  part  of  the  whole.  It  bears  traces  of 
all  the  influences  of  all  masses,  and  of  all  forces  of  the  rest 
of  the  world  according  to  the  way  it  is  interrelated  with  its 
surrounding  conditions. 

The  fixed  stars  have  so  far  proved  sufficient  for  our 
terrestrial  needs  to  serve  us  as  a  fundamental  body  for 


214  THE  MONIST. 

calculations  of  a  mechanical  nature;  but  here  the  problem 
of  absolute  space  presents  itself. 

We  know  positively  that  though  the  fixed  stars  are 
practically  a  fundamental  body  to  us  for  mechanical  meas- 
urements, they  are  shifting  about  among  themselves  and  no 
more  constitute  something  absolute  than  does  our  own 
earth ;  and  yet  there  has  risen  a  controversy  on  this  subject 
in  which  Ernst  Mach  applies  the  principle  of  relativity 
throughout  the  universe  while  Prof.  Alois  Hofler  stands  up 
for  what  he  calls  the  absolutist  theory.  We  will  hear  what 
Dr.  Frank  has  to  say  on  this  point : 

"Is  it  to  a  certain  extent  accidental,  or  is  it  essential,  that  the 
tatality  of  the  fixed  stars  coincides  with  that  fundamental  body  in 
relation  to  which  the  laws  of  Newton  hold  valid?  Or  to  put  it 
more  clearly:  If  the  fixed  stars  were  set  violently  in  motion  among 
each  other  and  hence  could  no  longer  constitute  a  fixed  body  of 
reference,  would  the  mechanical  processes  on  earth  proceed  exactly 
as  they  did  before?  For  instance,  would  the  Foucault  pendulum 
move  just  as  at  present,  even  though  it  now  turns  with  the  fixed 
stars,  whereas  in  that  case  it  would  not  be  quite  clear  which  con- 
stellation's revolution  it  should  join? 

"Were  everything  to  remain  as  of  old  the  fundamental  system 
of  reference  would  not  be  determined  by  the  fixed  stars  but  would 
only  accidentally  coincide  with  them,  and  would  in  reality  be 
some  merely  ideal  or  yet  undiscovered  body.  In  the  other  case  all 
mechanical  occurrences  on  earth  would  have  to  be  completely  altered 
to  correspond  with  the  promiscuous  movements  of  the  fixed  stars. 

"It  is  well  known  that  this  is  the  view  held  by  Ernst  Mach.  It 
alone  holds  with  consistent  firmness  to  physical  relativism,  and  it 
alone  answers  the  second  main  question  of  physics  in  the  relativistic 
sense. 

"The  opposite  view  is  represented  by  Alois  Hofler  in  his  studies 
on  the  current  philosophy  of  mechanics,  and  lately  by  G.  Hamel,  pro- 
fessor of  mechanics  at  the  technical  high  school  of  Briinn,  in  an 
essay  which  appeared  in  the  annual  report  of  the  German  mathemat- 
ical society  of  1909  on  'Space,  Time  and  Energy  as  a  priori  Forms 
of  Thought/ 

"Before  I  enter  upon  the  controversy  itself  I  would  like  further 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  215 

to  elucidate  Mach's  view  by  carrying  out  its  results  somewhat  farther. 
In  his  well-known  essay  on  the  History  and  Root  of  the  Principle 
of  the  Conservation  of  Energy^  Mach  ascribes  to  the  distant  masses 
in  space  a  direct  influence  on  the  motor  phenomena  of  the  earth 
which  supplements  the  influence  afforded  by  gravitation.  Of  course 
no  effect  of  gravitation  from  the  fixed  stars  upon  the  earth  can  be  ob- 
served, yet  in  spite  of  this  they  influence,  for  instance,  the  plane  of 
oscillation  of  the  Foucault  pendulum  because  in  Mach's  opinion  it 
remains  parallel  to  them. 

"The  question  now  arises  according  to  what  general  law  of 
nature  this  influence  operates  which  does  not,  like  gravity,  produce 
accelerations  but  velocities  instead.  Obviously  this  influence  must 
be  a  property  belonging  to  every  mass,  for  according  to  our  present 
conception  the  fixed  stars  of  course  are  precisely  the  same  sort  of 
masses  as  earthly  bodies. 

"However,  experience  teaches  us  that  terrestrial  masses  have 
no  more  influence  on  the  plane  of  oscillation  of  the  Foucault  pendu- 
lum than  has  the  changing  position  of  the  moon,  sun  and  planets ; 
but  on  the  other  hand  it  is  exactly  the  most  distant  masses,  the  fixed 
stars,  which  determine  its  plane  of  oscillation.  Accordingly  we  must 
either  assume  that  the  effect  is  directly  proportional  to  the  distance 
of  the  masses  (which  would  be  very  strange  indeed)  or  simply 
assume  that  this  effect  is  proportional  to  the  effective  masses  and 
independent  of  the  distance,  whence  the  dominant  influence  of  the 
more  remote,  as  the  far  greater  and  more  numerous,  bodies  would 
naturally  follow,  and  Mach  inclines  to  this  latter  view. 

"Mach's  view  shows  most  clearly  in  his  position  with  regard 
to  Newton's  famous  bucket  experiment.  In  this  Newton  intended 
to  show  that  the  centrifugal  force  produced  by  a  revolving  body  is 
due  not  to  its  relative  but  to  its  absolute  velocity  of  rotation.  He 
suspended  a  bucket  filled  with  water  by  a  vertical  cord,  twisted  the 
cord  quite  tightly  and  then  let  it  untwist  itself,  in  this  way  setting  the 
bucket  to  revolve  rapidly.  At  first  the  water  did  not  rotate  with  the 
bucket  and  therefore  the  bucket  had  a  velocity  of  rotation  with 
reference  to  the  water  while  in  the  meantime  the  surface  of  the 
water  remained  undisturbed.  In  time,  however,  friction  caused  the 
water  to  become  so  affected  by  the  rotary  motion  that  bucket  and 
water  revolved  like  one  homogeneous  mass  whereby  the  centrifugal 

11  Second  edition,  Leipsic,  1909 ;  English  translation  by  P.  E.  B.  Jourdain, 
Chicago,  1911. 


2l6  THE  MONIST. 

force  caused  the  water  to  rise  at  the  sides  of  the  bucket  and  the  sur- 
face became  concave. 

' 'Hence  it  is  evident  that  the  centrifugal  force  reached  its  great- 
est strength  at  the  moment  when  the  relative  motion  of  the  water 
with  respect  to  the  bucket  became  zero ;  hence  according  to  New- 
ton this  force  can  be  produced  only  by  the  absolute  rotary  motion  of 
the  water. 

"To  this  now  Mach  justly  protests  that  only  the  relative  rotation 
of  the  water  with  reference  to  the  fixed  stars  is  to  be  considered,  for 
this  system  of  the  fixed  stars  and  not  the  bucket  is  the  fundamental 
body.  And  indeed  at  first  the  water  was  at  rest  with  reference  to  the 
fixed  stars,  but  at  the  close  of  the  experiment  it  was  revolving. 
The  mass  of  the  bucket  compared  to  the  mass  of  the  fixed  stars  is 
an  entirely  negligible  quantity,  so  that  it  does  not  depend  in  the 
least  upon  the  rotation.  But  we  can  not  know,  adds  Mach,  how 
the  experiment  would  turn  out  if  the  sides  of  the  bucket  were  miles 
thick ;  and  by  this  he  apparently  means  so  thick  that  their  mass  would 
be  considerable  even  when  compared  with  the  mass  of  the  system  of 
fixed  stars.  Then  indeed  might  the  rotation  of  the  bucket  disturb 
the  action  of  the  fixed  stars. 

"Hofler  protests,  on  the  other  hand,  that  a  system  which  is 
symmetrical  round  its  axis  could  not  according  to  all  our  experience 
in  mechanics  produce  by  its  rotation  that  sort  of  an  effect  on  the 
water  within  it. 

"This  also  is  quite  true.  But  the  effect  of  the  masses  assumed 
by  Mach  is  such  that  it  can  not  be  expressed  in  our  ordinary  ex- 
periences with  mechanics  except  by  means  of  the  facts  of  the  iner- 
tia of  all  motion  with  reference  to  the  fixed  stars.  New  conditions 
such  as  the  rotation  of  an  enormously  thick  bucket  might  give  rise 
to  new  phenomena.  If  we  agree  with  Mach's  view  that  the  rotation 
of  the  plane  of  the  Foucault  pendulum  is  directly  produced  by  the 
masses  of  the  fixed  stars,  we  must  likewise  admit,  in  order  to  be  con- 
sistent, that  the  relative  rotation  of  the  very  thick  bucket  might  give 
rise  to  similar  effects  with  reference  to  the  water,  as  the  rotation  of 
the  system  of  the  fixed  stars  with  reference  to  the  earth  to  the  plane 
of  oscillation. 

"Hofler  expresses  his  contention  against  Mach's  thesis  in  the 
form  of  the  following  question:  If  in  Galileo's  time  the  sky  had 
been  clouded  over  and  had  never  become  clear  again  so  that  we 
would  never  have  been  able  to  have  taken  the  stars  into  our  calcu- 
lation, would  it  then  have  been  impossible  to  have  established  our 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  217 

present  mechanics  solely  by  the  aid  of  terrestrial  experiments? 
By  this  question  Hofler  means  to  say  that  if  the  connection  with  the 
fixed  stars  were  a  constituent  of  the  concept  of  uniform  motion,  we 
would  never  have  been  able  in  such  an  overclouded  world  to  have 
established  the  law  of  inertia,  for  instance,  whereas  in  reality  it  is 
clear  that  this  would  nevertheless  have  been  possible. 

"I  will  not  dwell  on  the  more  psychological  question  as  to 
whether  or  how  easily  this  would  have  been  possible,  but  will  only 
consider  now  the  logical  construction  of  mechanics  in  such  a  dark- 
ened world  on  the  hypothesis  that  easily  or  with  difficulty  in  one 
way  or  another  we  would  have  attained  to  our  present  knowledge 
of  mechanics. 

"Let  us  for  a  moment  imagine  ourselves  in  such  a  world. 
Above  our  heads  extends  a  uniform  vault  of  uninterrupted  gray  or 
black.  Were  we  to  shoot  projectiles  toward  the  south  we  would 
see  that  they  describe  paths  which  are  curved  towards  the  west;  if 
we  started  pendulums  to  vibrating  we  would  see  that  they  would  re- 
volve their  planes  of  oscillation  in  mysterious  periods — I  say  mys- 
terious because  we  might  perhaps  be  able  to  perceive  the  change  of 
day  and  night  as  an  alternation  of  light  and  darkness,  but  would  not 
be  able  to  refer  it  to  the  movements  of  celestial  bodies.  Perhaps 
at  first  we  would  surmise  that  the  motion  of  the  pendulum  could  be 
ascribed  to  optical  influences.  I  would  like  to  see  placed  in  such  a 
world  one  of  the  philosophers  who  regard  the  law  of  inertia  as  an 
a  priori  truth.  In  the  face  of  these  mysterious  curvatures  and  de- 
flections he  would  probably  find  no  adherents  and  he  would  not 
know  himself  what  to  make  of  his  own  standpoint. 

"Finally,  let  us  assume,  there  arises  a  dauntless  man,  the  Coper- 
nicus of  this  starless  world,  who  says  that  all  motions  proceed  spon- 
taneously in  a  straight  line,  but  that  this  straight  line  is  not  straight 
with  reference  to  the  earth  but  with  respect  to  a  purely  ideal  system 
of  reference  which  turns  in  a  direction  opposite  to  that  of  the  earth. 
The  period  of  this  rotation  is  supplied  by  the  period  of  the  Foucault 
pendulum. 

"This  man  would  of  course  deny  physical  relativism  upon  the 
earth,  for  in  his  opinion  terrestrial  processes  would  not  depend  only 
on  the  relative  velocities  of  terrestrial  bodies  but  on  something 
else  besides,  viz.,  their  velocities  with  respect  to  a  purely  ideal  sys- 
tem of  reference.  Nevertheless,  he  would  not  introduce  any  non- 
physical  element  because  for  the  purpose  of  the  physicist  a  purely 
ideal  system  of  reference  whose  motion  with  respect  to  an  em- 


2l8  THE  MONIST. 

pirical  system  is  known  serves  the  same  purpose  as  would  the  em- 
pirical system  itself.  This  bold  innovator  might  finally  refer  the 
words  'true  rest'  and  'true  motion'  to  his  ideal  fundamental  body 
and  so  ascribe  true  motion  and  only  apparent  rest  to  the  earth,  thus 
maintaining  a  mechanics  which  would  coincide  literally  with  that  of 
ours  to-day,  except  that  no  small  luminous  points  would  be  seen 
sparkling  in  connection  with  the  fundamental  body. 

"Hence  we  see  that  physical  relativism  is  not  a  necessary  tool 
of  the  physicist.  Apart,  perhaps,  from  the  psychological  improb- 
ability— of  which,  however,  nothing  more  positive  can  be  said — the 
possibility  of  the  development  here  indicated  is  logically  free  from 
objections  throughout,  and  therefore  the  same  is  also  true  "of  the 
possibility  of  a  nonrelativistic  physics. 

"But  I  would  like  to  strengthen  the  argument  of  Hofler  even 
somewhat  further.  That  is  to  say,  I  would  ask  whether  the  world 
in  which  we  live  is  then  really  so  essentially  different  from  that 
fictitious  one.  Imagine  the  dark  roof  which  conceals  the  sky  placed 
somewhat  higher  so  that  there  is  room  beneath  it  for  the  fixed  stars, 
perhaps  as  the  dark  background  which  may  be  seen  nightly  in  the 
starry  sky.  The  whole  difference  then  consists  in  the  fact  that  not 
only  the  Foucault  pendulum  and  similar  appliances  move  with  ref- 
erence to  the  earth,  but  enormously  greater  masses  as  well — all  the 
twinkling  lights  of  the  sky  by  which  the  thought  of  a  fundamental 
body  in  motion  with  respect  to  the  earth  is  psychologically  greatly 
facilitated,  but  logically  is  not  much  changed.  Now  imagine  the 
sky  of  this  earlier  dark  world  suddenly  illuminated ;  then  we  would 
see  that  the  fictitious  system  of  reference  is  closely  linked  to  enormous 
cosmic  masses,  and  it  would  be  easy  enough  to  accept  Mach's  hy- 
pothesis that  these  masses  condition  the  fundamental  system .... 

"If  a  distinction  must  be  drawn  between  the  respective  values 
of  the  conceptions  of  Mach  and  Hofler,  it  is  as  follows :  Mach's  view 
adds  decidedly  more  to  the  observed  facts ;  for  that  it  retains  phys- 
ical relativism  does  not  involve  freedom  from  hypothesis,  because 
at  best  this  relativism  is  theory  and  not  fact.  Mach  sets  up,  hypo- 
thetically  of  course,  a  new  formal  natural  law  with  regard  to  the 
action  of  masses  existing  side  by  side  with  gravitation,  affecting 
the  experiment  very  materially  but  unable  to  raise  any  claim  to  the 
simplest  description  of  actual  conditions. 

"The  other  view,  which  simply  introduces  the  system  of  ref- 
erence procured  by  observation  of  the  terrestrial  and  celestial  move- 
ments without  asking  whence  all  this  is  derived,  represents  the  pres- 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY. 

ent  state  of  our  knowledge  most  adequately  without  any  arbitrary 
addendum  but  also  without  giving  the  spirit  of  inquiry  any  incentive 
to  new  experiments. 

"It  is  the  old  contrast  between  the  most  exact  and  least  hypo- 
thetical representation  possible  of  the  known  science,  and  progressive 
inquiry  after  new  things  in  more  or  less  daring  and  fantastic  hypoth- 
eses. But  Mach  in  this  case  stands  in  the  opposite  camp  as  in  most 
other  cases  where  his  repugnance  to  all  hypothesis  has  made  him  a 
pioneer  in  the  phenomenological  direction .... 

"I  therefore  believe  I  have  proved  that  we  can  grant  the  follow- 
ing: Physical  phenomena  do  not  depend  only  on  the  relative  motion 
of  bodies  without  at  the  same  time  admitting  the  possibility  of  the 
concept  of  an  absolute  motion  in  the  philosophical  sense."* 

Strange  that  Mach,  with  his  reluctance  to  introduce 
anything  hypothetical  except  what  is  absolutely  indispen- 
sable, should  range  on  the  side  of  the  theorists,  and  after 
some  reflection  I  believe  that  there  may  be  a  slight  hitch  in 
Dr.  Frank's  interpretation  of  Mach's  view. 

First  I  myself,  from  my  own  point  of  view,  would  refuse 
to  call  the  principle  of  relativity  an  hypothesis;  it  is  an 
a  priori  proposition,  a  theorem,  or  if  you  prefer,  a  postu- 
late of  pure  thought  which  either  holds  good  universally, 
or  has  no  validity  whatever.  So  far  as  I  know,  Mach  has 
not  discussed  this  side  of  the  subject  but  he  has  instinctively 
acted  upon  this  view,  and  I  would  say  that  there  is  a 
greater  hypothetical  element  in  the  assumption  that  the 
theorem  2  X  2  =  4,  or  any  other  proposition  of  the  same 
kind,  holds  good  only  for  our  earth  but  not  for  Mars  and 
Venus,  than  to  say  that  it  holds  good  also  for  the  fixed 
stars  and  in  the  possible  worlds  outside  of  our  Milky  Way. 
Accordingly,  whatever  Mach's  personal  opinion  may  be, 
I  would  regard  the  universal  application  of  the  principle 
of  relativity  as  less  complicated  and  more  free  from  hypo- 

*  This  last  paragraph  is  printed  in  spaced  letters  which  indicates  the  em- 
phasis of  the  author,  and  so  we  print  the  text  of  his  summary  in  the  original. 
Dr.  Frank  says :  "Die  physikalischen  Erscheinungen  hangen  nicht  nur  von  der 
Relativbewegung  der  Korper  ab,  ohne  doch  damit  die  Moglichkeit  des  Be- 
griffes  einer  absoluten  Bewegung  im  philosophischen  Sinne  zuzugeben." 


22O  THE  MONIST. 

<• 

thetical  elements  than  its  limitation  to  a  portion  of  the 
world. 

I  can  not  as  yet  make  up  my  mind  to  believe  that  our 
system  of  the  Milky  Way  which  furnishes  us  the  grand 
sight  of  the  fixed  stars  is  an  ultimate  possessing  the  charac- 
teristics of  absolute  space. 

According  to  Kant  the  totality  of  the  fixed  stars  which 
are  thickest  in  the  Milky  Way  forms  a  great  system  (the 
system  of  the  Milky  Way)  and  our  sun  as  well  as  all  the 
visible  fixed  stars  belongs  to  it.  Kant  believes  that  this,  our 
own  universe,  which  in  the  Milky  Way  appears  to  us  as  an 
enormous  ring  but  together  with  the  totality  of  the  fixed 
stars  must  resemble  an  oblate  spheroid,  is  not  the  only  cosmic 
system,  but  that  there  are  other  similar  systems  outside  of  it 
and  that  they  too  whirl  on  through  the  infinity  of  space,  in 
company  with  our  Milky  Way  system,  around  some  center 
of  their  own;  and  this  very  center  of  many  Milky  Ways 
may  partake  of  a  motion  the  observation  of  which  lies 
hopelessly  beyond  our  ken.  Accordingly  the  space  condi- 
tions of  the  Milky  Way  may  serve  us  as  absolute  space, 
but  there  is  a  probability  that  this  space  is  not  more  abso- 
lute than  are  the  space  relations  in  a  quick  but  quietly  mov- 
ing train  to  the  passengers. 

Another  point  where  we  feel  justified  in  doubting  Dr. 
Frank's  exposition  is  the  statement  that  Mach  hypothet- 
ically  assumes  a  new  law  of  nature  as  to  the  efficacy  of 
masses,  besides  the  law  of  gravitation.  The  passage  in 
Mach's  writings  to  which  Dr.  Frank  refers  does  not  (in 
my  opinion)  suggest  the  idea  of  an  additional  law  of  nature 
according  to  which  the  distant  fixed  stars  should  exercise 
a  mysterious  influence  on  the  Foucault  pendulum.  We  will 
later  on  let  Mach  speak  for  himself.  In  our  opinion  it 
seems  that  it  would  be  sufficient  to  ascribe  the  rotation  of 
the  pendulum  to  its  inertia  while  the  earth  revolves  round 
itself,  and  this  takes  place  in  the  space  in  which  the  earth 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  221 

has  its  motion,  viz.,  the  space  of  the  Milky  Way  system. 
The  pendulum  remains  in  the  plane  of  oscillation  in  which 
it  started  while  the  earth  turns  around  underneath.  If 
there  are  influences  at  work  beyond  the  expanse  of  the 
space  of  the  fixed  stars  in  our  Milky  Way  system,  they 
must  affect  the  totality  of  our  system  and  would  therefore 
be  contained  in  its  space  conditions ;  acting  with  an  unfail- 
ing constancy  they  could  not  be  separated  from  the  prop- 
erties of  our  space  and  would  scarcely  be  discoverable. 

There  seems  to  me  no  need  of  inventing  a  new  force 
besides  gravitation.  The  law  of  inertia  seems  to  explain 
the  Foucault  pendulum  experiment  satisfactorily. 

The  fixed  stars  as  a  totality  remain  in  their  places  (at 
least  as  far  as  concerns  the  experiment)  and  the  plane  in 
which  the  pendulum  swings  keeps  its  original  direction; 
thus  the  apparent  motions  of  both  coincide.  Their  space 
relations  (the  space  relations  of  the  pendulum  and  of  the 
fixed  stars)  are  the  same,  and  there  is  no  need  to  assume 
the  existence  of  any  unknown  force  exercised  by  the  fixed 
stars  upon  the  pendulum. 

ERNST   MACH. 

We  will  let  Mach  state  his  views  in  his  own  words : 

"Obviously  it  does  not  matter  whether  we  think  of  the  earth  as 
turning  round  on  its  axis,  or  at  rest  while  the  celestial  bodies  revolve 
round  it.  Geometrically  these  are  exactly  the  same  case  of  a  relative 
rotation  of  the  earth  and  of  the  celestial  bodies  with  respect  to  one 
another.  Only,  the  first  representation  is  astronomically  more  con- 
venient and  simpler. 

"But  if  we  think  of  the  earth  at  rest  and  the  other  celestial 
bodies  revolving  round  it,  there  is  no  flattening  of  the  earth,  no 
Foucault's  experiment,  and  so  on — at  least  according  to  our  usual 
conception  of  the  law  of  inertia. 

"Now,  one  can  solve  the  difficulty  in  two  ways:  Either  all  mo- 
tion is  absolute,  or  our  law  of  inertia  is  wrongly  expressed.  Neu- 
mann12 preferred  the  first  supposition,  I,  the  second.  The  law  of 
12  Ueber  die  Principien  der  Galilei-Newt on 'schen  Theorie.  Leipsic,  1870. 


222  THE  MONIST. 

inertia  must  be  so  conceived  that  exactly  the  same  thing  results 
from  the  second  supposition  as  from  the  first.  By  this  it  will  be  evi- 
dent that,  in  its  expression,  regard  must  be  paid  to  the  masses  of 
the  universe. 

"In  ordinary  terrestrial  cases,  it  will  answer  our  purposes  quite 
well  to  reckon  the  direction  and  velocity  with  respect  to  the  top  of  a 
tower  or  a  corner  of  a  room;  in  ordinary  astronomical  cases,  one 
or  other  of  the  stars  will  suffice.  But  because  we  can  also  choose 
other  corners 'of  rooms,  another  pinnacle,  or  other  stars,  the  view 
may  easily  arise  that  we  do  not  need  such  a  point  at  all  from  which 
to  reckon.  But  this  is  a  mistake ;  such  a  system  of  coordinates  has 
a  value  only  if  it  can  be  determined  by  means  of  bodies. . . . 

"If  we  wish  to  apply  the  law  of  inertia  in  an  earthquake,  the 
terrestrial  points  of  reference  would  leave  us  in  the  lurch,  and,  con- 
vinced of  their  uselessness,  we  would  grope  after  celestial  ones. 
But,  with  these  better  ones,  the  same  thing  would  happen  as  soon 
as  the  stars  showed  movements  which  were  very  noticeable.  When 
the  variations  of  the  positions  of  the  fixed  stars  with  respect  to  one 
another  cannot  be  disregarded,  the  laying  down  of  a  system  of  co- 
ordinates has  reached  an  end.  It  ceases  to  be  immaterial  whether 
we  take  this  or  that  star  as  point  of  reference ;  and  we  can  no  longer 
reduce  these  systems  to  one  another.  We  ask  for  the  first  time 
which  star  we  are  to  choose,  and  in  this  case  easily  see  that  the  stars 
cannot  be  treated  indifferently,  but  that  because  we  can  give  prefer- 
ence to  none,  the  influence  of  all  must  be  taken  into  consideration. 

"We  can,  in  the  application  of  the  law  of  inertia,  disregard  any 
particular  body,  provided  that  we  have  enough  other  bodies  which 
are  fixed  with  respect  to  one  another.  If  a  tower  falls,  this  does  not 
matter  to  us ;  we  have  others.  If  Sirius  alone,  like  a  shooting  star, 
shot  through  the  heavens,  it  would  not  disturb  us  very  much ;  other 
stars  would  be  there.  But  what  would  become  of  the  law  of  inertia 
if  the  whole  of  the  heavens  began  to  move  and  the  stars  swarmed 
in  confusion?  How  would  we  apply  it  then?  How  would  it  have 
to  be  expressed  then?  We  need  not  worry  about  one  body  as  long 
as  we  have  others  enough.  Only  in  the  case  of  a  shattering  of  the 
universe  we  learn  that  all  bodies,  each  with  its  share,  are  of  im- 
portance in  the  law  of  inertia.  . . . 

"Yet  another  example :  A  free  body,  when  acted  upon  by  an  in- 
stantaneous couple,  moves  so  that  its  central  ellipsoid  with  fixed  cen- 
ter rolls  without  slipping  on  a  tangent-plane  parallel  to  the  plane  of 
the  couple.  This  is  a  motion  in  consequence  of  inertia.  Here  the  body 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  223 

makes  very  strange  motions  with  respect  to  the  celestial  bodies. 
Now,  do  we  think  that  these  bodies,  without  which  one  cannot 
describe  the  motion  imagined,  are  without  influence  on  this  motion? 
Does  not  that  to  which  one  must  appeal  explicitly  or  implicitly  when 
one  wishes  to  describe  a  phenomenon  belong  to  the  most  essential 
conditions,  to  the  causal  nexus  of  the  phenomenon?  The  distant 
heavenly  bodies  have,  in  our  example,  no  influence  on  the  accelera- 
tion, but  they  have  on  the  velocity." 

Now  follows  the  passage  to  which  Dr.  Frank  obviously 
refers : 

"Now,  what  share  has  every  mass  in  the  determination  of  direc- 
tion and  velocity  in  the  law  of  inertia?  No  definite  answer  can  be 
given  to  this  by  our  experiences.  We  only  know  that  the  share  of 
the  nearest  masses  vanishes  in  comparison  with  that  of  the  farthest. 
We  would,  then,  be  able  completely  to  make  out  the  facts  known  to 
us  if,  for  example,  we  were  to  make  the  simple  supposition  that  all 
bodies  act  in  the  way  of  determination  proportionately  to  their 
masses  and  independently  of  the  distance,  or  proportionately  to  the 
distance,  and  so  on.  Another  expression  would  be:  In  so  far  as 
bodies  are  so  distant  from  one  another  that  they  contribute  no  notice- 
able acceleration  to  one  another,  all  distances  vary  proportionately 
to  one  another." 

We  do  not  here  understand  Mach  to  fall  back  on  the 
assumption  of  a  new  kind  of  force,  and  if  we  must  grant 
that  the  distant  masses  exercise  a  dominant  influence  while 
the  influence  of  the  nearest  ones  (of  the  earth,  the  moon, 
and  the  sun)  vanishes,  we  would  say  that  this  is  due  to  the 
constancy  of  the  distant  masses  which,  as  it  were,  is  an 
inherent  and  inalienable  part  of  all  mass  in  the  entire  sys- 
tem and  may  be  said  to  characterize  its  space  conditions. 

In  speaking  of  "space  conditions"  I  am  conscious  of 
using  a  term  which  Mach  would  repudiate,  for  he  claims 
that  for  a  comprehension  of  the  concatenation  of  events, 
the  notions  of  time  and  space  are  redundant.  He  says 
(loc.  cit.  pp.  60-61)  : 

"To  say  the  least,  it  is  superfluous  in  our  consideration  of  causal- 
ity to  drag  in  time  and  space.  Since  we  only  recognize  what  we 


224  THE   MONIST. 

call  time  and  space  by  certain  phenomena,  spatial  and  temporal  deter- 
minations are  only  determinations  by  means  of  other  phenomena. 
If,  for  example,  we  express  the  positions  of  earthly  bodies  as  func- 
tions of  the  time,  that  is  to  say,  as  functions  of  the  earth's  angle  of 
rotation,  we  have  simply  determined  the  dependence  of  the  positions 
of  the  earthly  bodies  on  one  another. 

"The  earth's  angle  of  rotation  is  very  ready  to  our  hand,  and 
thus  we  easily  substitute  it  for  other  phenomena  which  are  connected 
with  it  but  less  accessible  to  us ;  it  is  a  kind  of  money  which  we  spend 
to  avoid  the  inconvenient  trading  with  phenomena,  so  that  the  pro- 
verb "Time  is  money"  has  also  here  a  meaning.  We  can  elim- 
inate time  from  every  law  of  nature  by  putting  in  its  place  a  phenom- 
enon dependent  on  the  earth's  angle  of  rotation. 

"The  same  holds  of  space.  We  know  positions  in  space  by  the 
affection  of  our  retina,  or  our  optical  or  other  measuring  apparatus. 
And  our  x,  y,  z  in  the  equations  of  physics  are,  indeed,  nothing  else 
than  convenient  names  for  these  affections.  Spatial  determinations 
are,  therefore,  again  determinations  of  phenomena  by  means  of  other 
phenomena. 

"The  present  tendency  of  physics  is  to  represent  every  phenom- 
enon as  a  function  of  other  phenomena  and  of  certain  spatial  and 
temporal  positions.  If,  now,  we  imagine  the  spatial  and  temporal 
positions  replaced  in  the  above  manner,  in  the  equations  in  question, 
we  obtain  simply  every  phenomenon  as  function  of  other  phenomena. 

"Thus  the  law  of  causality  is  sufficiently  characterized  by  saying 
that  it  is  the  presupposition  of  the  mutual  dependence  of  phenomena. 
Certain  idle  questions,  for  example,  whether  the  cause  precedes  or 
is  simultaneous  with  the  effect,  then  vanish  by  themselves." 

We  understand  that  Mach  endeavors  to  eliminate  the 
terms  time  and  space,  because  he  wishes  to  correct  the 
common  notion  which  regards  space  as  a  big  box  into 
which  the  world  has  been  packed.  Mach  says: 

"Space  and  time  are  not  here  conceived  as  independent  entities, 
but  as  forms  of  the  dependence  of  the  phenomena  on  one  another. 
I  subscribe,  then,  to  the  principle  of  relativity,  which  is  also  firmly 
upheld  in  my  Mechanics  and  Warmelehre"™ 

We  agree  with  Mach.    There  is  no  time  in  itself;  there 

18  Cf.  "Zeit  und  Raum  physikalisch  betrachtet,"  in  Erkenntnis  und  Irrtum. 
Leipsic,  1905  (ad  ed.  1906,  pp.  434-448)  ;  See  also  Space  and  Geometry,  pp.  94  ff. 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  225 

is  no  space  in  itself.  Nevertheless,  Mach  has  given  much 
attention  to  physical  space  and  appreciates  the  important 
part  which  it  plays  not  only  in  the  formation  of  our  space- 
conception,  but  also  in  the  actual  world,  for  every  spot  of 
space  possesses  physical  qualities  according  to  the  particles 
of  mass  which  are  there  aggregated.  Mach  says: 

"Since  the  positions  in  space  of  the  material  parts  can  be  recog- 
nized only  by  their  states,  we  can  also  say  that  all  the  states  of  the 
material  parts  depend  upon  one  another. 

"The  physical  space  which  I  have  in  mind — and  which,  at  the 
same  time,  contains  time  in  itself — is  thus  nothing  other  than  de- 
pendence of  phenomena  on  one  another.  A  complete  physics,  which 
would  know  this  fundamental  dependence,  would  have  no  more  need 
of  special  considerations  of  space  and  time,  for  these  latter  consid- 
erations would  already  be  included  in  the  former  knowledge." 

The  same  idea  is  expressed  by  Mach  in  his  Essay 
"Ueber  den  Zeitsinn  des  Ohres:14 

"Physics  sets  out  to  represent  every  phenomenon  as  a  function 
of  time.  The  motion  of  a  pendulum  serves  as  the  measure  of  time. 
Thus,  physics  really  expresses  every  phenomenon  as  a  function  of 
the  length  of  the  pendulum.  We  may  remark  that  this  also  happens 
when  forces,  say,  are  represented  as  functions  of  the  distance ;  for 
the  conception  of  force  (acceleration)  already  contains  that  of  time. 
If  one  were  to  succeed  in  expressing  every  phenomenon — physical 
and  psychical — as  a  function  of  the  phenomenon  of  pendulum- 
motion,  this  would  only  prove  that  all  phenomena  are  so  connected 
that  any  one  of  them  can  be  represented  as  a  function  of  any  other. 
Physically,  then,  time  is  the  representability  of  any  phenomenon  as 
a  function  of  any  other  one." 

We  do  not  deny  the  truth  of  Mach's  view.  Neverthe- 
less time  and  space  are  very  convenient  terms  denoting 
two  categories  of  certain  interrelations  (he  would  call 
them  interdependencies)  in  the  flux  of  things.  Popular 
terms  mostly  originate  because  there  is  a  need  of  them, 
and  it  seems  to  me  it  would  be  wiser  to  correct  the  errors 
connected  with  them  than  to  drop  them.  If  we  pursue  the 

"Sitgb.  der  Wien.  Akad.,  1865.    Compare  Conservation  of  Energy,  p.  90. 


226  THE  MONIST. 

latter  policy  we  shall  find  ourselves  obliged  to  reinvent  a 
new  collective  term  for  certain  classes  of  relations  which 
belong  together  and  can  not  be  identified  with  other  rela- 
tions. The  space  and  time  relations  are  radically  different 
from  those  of  a  purely  physical,  chemical  or  psychological 
nature. 

We  need  not  fear  to  retain  the  old  terms,  space  and 
time,  if  we  only  bear  in  mind  that  there  is  neither  absolute 
space  nor  absolute  time  but  that  the  words  denote  relations. 
It  seems  to  me  that  when  Kant  speaks  of  the  ideality  of 
space  and  time  and  insists  on  their  non-existence  as  ob- 
jective beings  (We sen  or  Wesenheiten)  he  attempts  to  say 
the  same  as  Mach  who  declares  that  they  are  not  "inde- 
pendent entities." 

The  conclusion  at  which  we  arrive  in  considering  the 
nature  of  time  and  of  space,  be  it  from  our  standpoint  of 
philosophy  or  from  Mach's  physical  point  of  view,  may 
be  expressed  in  one  word,  that  their  most  obvious  char- 
acteristic is  relativity. 

CONCLUSION. 

Professor  Mach  says  in  one  of  his  notes  quoted  above, 
"I  subscribe  then  to  the  principle  of  relativity,"  and  so  do 
I.  Indeed  I  go  one  step  further.  I  consider  relativity  as 
an  inherent  quality  of  existence  and  so  I  adopt  the  prin- 
ciple of  it  not  as  a  result  of  experience  but  on  a  priori 
grounds.  The  principle  of  relativity,  however,  is  fre- 
quently stated  by  relativity  physicists  as  if  the  old  ideal 
of  science  in  its  objective  significance  had  to  be  abandoned, 
as  if  physics  had  to  be  remodeled,  and  as  if  the  proclama- 
tion of  the  principle  of  relativity  indicated  a  new  departure 
from  our  traditional  methods.  This  is  not  so,  and  I  must 
insist  that  the  principle  of  relativity  has  always  been  sub- 
consciously in  the  minds  of  scientists.  Only  it  has  lately 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  227 

been  forced  upon  the  attention  of  physicists  by  the  progress 
in  astronomical  measurements. 

How  helpful  the  emphasis  recently  laid  upon  the  prin- 
ciple of  relativity  will  prove  remains  to  be  seen.  Its  ardent 
adherents  exhibit  great  zeal  which  in  many  directions 
seems  to  be  misdirected,  and  it  appears  to  me  that  in  spite 
of  the  correctness  of  the  underlying  idea  their  hopes  are 
greatly  exaggerated.  After  a  while  when  the  opponents 
of  the  principle  of  relativity  will  understand  that  its  truth 
is  as  much  a  matter  of  course  as  the  truth  of  the  law  of 
conservation  of  matter  and  energy,  the  contentions  about 
it  will  cease  and  the  evolution  of  science  will  no  longer 
show  evidence  of  excitement  but  will  continue  in  its  old 
quiet  way. 

There  is  more  philosophy  in  our  science  than  the  school 
of  empiricists  are  inclined  to  believe.  It  is  very  desirable 
that  in  familiarizing  themselves  with  philosophy,  these 
scientists  should  not  fall  back  on  the  old  systems  of  a  vision- 
ary absolute,  but  they  should  adopt  the  philosophy  of  sci- 
ence, the  only  philosophy  which  is  not  a  mere  ingenious 
dream,  and  possesses  objective  significance. 

The  philosophy  of  science  is  the  philosophy.  It  is  the 
indispensable  introduction  to  the  study  of  any  science  and 
furnishes  the  basis  for  scientific  method  as  well  as  a  general 
survey  of  the  assured  results  of  all  the  several  sciences. 
If  the  philosophy  of  science  had  been  better  known,  the 
principle  of  relativity  had  at  once  been  rightly  understood 
and  the  vagaries  of  many  mystifying  contentions  would 

have  been  avoided. 

*       *       * 

The  purpose  of  this  article  is  to  set  forth  in  general 
outlines  the  truth  and  significance  of  the  principle  of  rela- 
tivity, not  to  present  an  exhaustive  treatment  of  it  in  all 
its  phases  and  applications.  We  must  bear  in  mind  that 
in  dealing  with  the  several  innumerable  problems  of  exist- 


228  THE  MONIST. 

ence  science  introduces  a  method  which  possesses  certain 
limitations  due  to  conditions  which  originate  through  some 
fictions  of  an  apparently  arbitrary  nature  assumed  for  the 
sake  of  isolating  the  object  of  investigation  and  concentrat- 
ing upon  it  our  attention. 

We  must  bear  in  mind  that  we  behold  an  object  by 
focusing  our  eyes  upon  it  and  that  only  thereby  can  we 
form  a  picture  of  the  object.  It  is  a  fiction  to  behold  an 
object  as  if  it  were  a  thing  by  itself  and  it  is  positively 
impossible  to  see  anything  as  it  is  in  all  its  relations  and 
with  all  its  changes,  past,  present  and  future.  Nor  would 
such  a  comprehension  of  the  object  in  all  its  entirety  be 
desirable,  for  in  the  omneity  of  its  relations  we  would  see 
the  whole  universe  while  the  special  feature  which  concerns 
us  sinks  into  insignificance.  The  same  is  true  of  science. 
Each  of  the  several  sciences  selects  its  own  field  of  investi- 
gation and  thus  constitutes  a  definite  domain  of  abstraction 
for  the  sake  of  concentrating  all  attention  upon  it.  For 
mechanics  and  for  the  measurements  of  motion  in  space,  we 
need  a  reference  point  which  must  be  able  to  be  considered 
stationary,  and  if  that  is  not  the  case  we  must  refer  both 
the  movable  place  of  observation,  viz.,  the  reference  point 
(R)  and  the  object  observed  (O)  to  one  common  system, 
which  could  be  treated  as,  or  must  so  far  as  R  and  O  are 
concerned,  actually  be,  stable. 

We  conclude  by  repeating  that  there  is  nothing  abso- 
lute ;  all  real  and  actual  existences,  all  concrete  things  and 
happenings  are  relative,  and  if  there  is  any  thing  that  in  a 
certain  sense  deserves  the  name  absolute  it  is  the  truth  as 
described  in  our  mental  fictions,  the  laws  of  purely  formal 
thought,  the  eternal  uniformities  of  purely  formal  rela- 
tions such  as  we  know  from  mathematics  and  all  the  other 
purely  formal  sciences;  but  even  they  are  absolute  only  in 
the  sense  of  constituting  an  entire  system  the  truth  of 
which  is  absolute,  viz.,  it  stands  aloof  and  is  founded  in  it- 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  RELATIVITY.  22Q 

self  as  a  world  of  necessary  conclusions  built  up  in  the  field 
of  anyness  to  serve  as  models  for  any  conditions  in  any 
world  actual  or  imaginary.  And  this  absolute,  this  system 
of  mental  construction  is  after  all  a  system  of  relations. 

The  more  we  ponder  on  the  nature  of  existence,  the 
more  we  shall  understand  the  sweeping  significance  of 

relativity. 

P.  c. 


INVENTORS  I  HAVE  MET.* 

AJY  one  who  has  been  a  professor  of  physics  in  a  large 
city  for  several  decades,  unless  he  has  earned  a  repu- 
tation for  the  crudest  and  densest  Philistinism,  must  have 
made  the  acquaintance  of  divers  thinkers  and  inventors 
who  have  taken  counsel  with  him  in  their  perplexities — 
thinkers  of  all  kinds,  schooled  and  unschooled,  sanguine 
and  timid,  those  that  solve  problems  and  those  that  create 
them;  thinkers,  suspicious  and  confiding,  ambitious  and 
practical ;  inventors  at  any  price,  and  inventors  on  occasion. 
It  is  obvious  that  the  number  of  actual  or  alleged  in- 
ventors in  this  company  is  greater  than  that  of  silent  stu- 
dious, self-centered  thinkers.  Practical  discomfort  is  felt 
more  often  and  to  a  greater  extent  than  the  rarer  purely 
intellectual  discomfort  which  is  the  heritage  of  men  on  a 
higher  spiritual  plane.  Many  fruitless  hours  may  be  spent 
in  such  consultations,  but  many  a  bit  of  psychological  illu- 
mination may  be  gained  and  many  a  glance  into  the  em- 
bryology of  technique  and  science.  We  may  add  right 
here  that  the  unlettered,  unschooled  or  wild  thinkers  and 
inventors  are  the  most  interesting  and  instructive. 

*       *       * 

One  day  a  gentleman  was  announced  who  had  some- 
thing of  importance  to  communicate  to  me.  He  told  me 
that  he  had  taken  a  narrow  tube  full  of  liquid,  closed 
at  the  upper  end  and  open  below,  from  which  of  course 

*  Translated  from  the  German  by  Lydia  G.  Robinson. 


INVENTORS  I   HAVE  MET.  23! 

nothing  could  flow  because  of  the  pressure  of  air;  then 
he  gave  it  a  charge  of  electricity,  whereupon  the  liquid 
began  at  once  to  flow.  From  this  he  drew  the  rash  con- 
clusion that  the  electric  charge  removed  the  air  pressure. 
I  gave  instructions  that  an  appointment  be  made  with  this 
gentleman  for  a  free  hour  in  the  afternoon  in  order  to  make 
the  experiment.  But  since  one  can  easily  tell  whether  or 
not  a  man  is  undertaking  something  from  a  purely  theo- 
retical interest,  I  said  to  the  attendant  in  the  laboratory, 
"The  gentleman  probably  thinks  he  can  drive  a  railway 
train  with  the  electrical  machine."  In  the  afternoon  con- 
siderably before  the  appointed  time  the  stranger  put  in  an 
appearance.  "Are  you  thinking  of  driving  a  railroad 
train  ?"  the  attendant  asked  him  by  way  of  filling  the  inter- 
val with  conversation.  Immediately  and  without  losing 
another  word  the  gentleman  seized  his  hat  and  was  gone 
forever.  So  I  had  guessed  his  purpose  correctly,  and  had 
deprived  him  of  the  pleasure  of  taking  me  into  his  con- 
fidence in  his  alleged  lucrative  undertaking.  Forty  years 
have  passed  since  then,  and  the  man  has  probably  calmed 
down  in  the  meantime. 


There  are  people  who  become  greatly  excited  over  every 
scientific  novelty,  whose  imagination  busies  itself  at  once 
in  a  new  field  without  any  special  participation  on  the  part 
of  their  intelligence,  and  whose  desire  it  is  to  make  an  in- 
vention or  a  discovery  in  this  field  at  any  cost.  So  after 
the  discovery  of  the  Foucault  rotation  of  the  pendulum's 
plane  of  oscillation  many  experiments  were  made  known 
by  which  it  was  thought  this  rotation  could  be  perceived 
in  water  standing  in  a  cylindrical  tub  across  whose  surface 
coal-dust  had  been  lightly  strewn ;  or  again  in  a  horizontal 
disk  suspended  by  a  thread,  or  in  a  scale-beam  similarly 
suspended. 


232  THE  MONIST. 

But  obviously  these  experiments  are  not  sensible.  For 
instance,  if  a  horizontal  disk  is  actually  at  rest  with  ref- 
erence to  the  earth  it  has  of  course  the  component  of  rota- 
tion of  the  earth  around  the  perpendicular  corresponding 
to  geographical  latitude ;  therefore  the  disk  can  not  hence- 
forth alter  its  position  with  reference  to  its  terrestrial  sur- 
roundings. Under  other  circumstances,  however,  it  has  an 
angular  velocity  around  the  perpendicular  due  to  some  im- 
pulse, to  a  draft  of  air,  or  the  thread's  momentum  of  rota- 
tion, and  hence  has  no  connection  whatever  to  the  Foucault 
rotation.  One  young  man  could  not  accept  these  reflec- 
tions at  all  but  persisted  in  repeating  the  experiment  thus 
described  by  which  he  gained  the  interest  of  an  old  gentle- 
man who  observed  in  them  "sometimes"  the  genuine  Fou- 
cault rotation. 

To  be  sure,  Professor  Tumlirz  has  recently  performed 
an  experiment  which,  while  externally  similar  to  this,  is 
correct.  By  this  experiment  the  rotation  of  the  earth  can 
be  imitated,  if  the  utmost  care  is  taken,  by  the  direction 
of  the  current  of  water  flowing  axially  out  of  a  cylindrical 
vessel.  Further  details  are  to  be  found  in  an  article  by 
Tumlirz  in  the  Sitzungsberichte  der  Wiener  Akademie, 
Vol.  117,  1908.  I  happened  to  know  the  origin  of  the 
thought  that  gave  rise  to  this  invention.  Tumlirz  noticed 
that  the  water  flowing  somewhat  unsymmetrically  in  a 
glass  funnel  assumed  a  swift  rotation  in  the  neck  of  the 
funnel  so  that  it  formed  a  whirl  of  air  in  the  axis  of  the 
flowing  jet.  This  put  it  in  his  mind  to  increase  the  slight 
angular  velocity  of  the  water  at  rest  with  reference  to  the 
earth,  by  contraction  in  the  axis. 

The  above-mentioned  imaginative  young  man  also  con- 
structed a  telephone  by  a  static  electrical  charge,  and  this 
invention  likewise  proved  a  delusion.  Experimenting  within 
the  space  of  one  room  he  had  heard  his  own  voice  both  as 
transmitter  and  receiver  at  the  same  time.  Very  often  an 


INVENTORS  I   HAVE  MET.  233 

illusory  invention  bears  witness  simply  to  the  ardent  hopes 
of  its  originator. 


Another  young  man  declared  that  the  theories  of  Gali- 
leo with  regard  to  falling  bodies  and  projectiles  which  he 
had  learned  in  school  were  false;  that  the  projected  stone 
forms  an  entirely  different  problem  from  the  falling  stone ; 
that  the  stone  that  is  thrown  is  carried  through  the  air 
and  in  the  projection  gravity  is  overcome.  To  this  man 
the  Aristotelian  distinction  between  the  natural  falling 
motion  and  the  violent  motion  of  throwing  is  still  valid. 
The  fusion  of  the  two  primitive  ideas  into  a  unified  whole 
had  not  yet  taken  place  in  his  understanding. 

*       *       * 

Such  a  reversion  to  the  primitive  condition  of  science 
is  not  an  isolated  one.  We  may  therefore  conclude  that 
after  a  disturbing  interruption  of  the  development  of  civili- 
zation science  would  again  pursue  almost  the  same  course 
of  evolution  it  had  previously  followed,  although  this  of 
course  would  not  preclude  minor  accidental  discrepancies. 
Science  has  also  its  own  natural  embryology  which  is  re- 
vealed through  epistemology.  Once  I  received  an  inquiry 
from  the  United  States  about  the  hydrostatic  paradox 
which  after  Archimedes  has  been  explained  by  Stevinus 
and  for  the  third  time  by  Pascal.  The  American  writer 
declared  that  he  could  not  understand  how  the  pressure 
at  the  bottom  of  a  vessel  could  depend  upon  anything  else 
than  upon  the  weight  of  the  liquid  resting  on  the  bottom. 
Of  course  this  was  a  very  natural  idea.  I  now  proceeded 
to  expound  to  the  gentleman  that  the  pressure  at  the  bot- 
tom can  not  depend  on  the  weight  of  the  liquid  resting  on 
the  bottom,  but  only  on  that  portion  of  the  weight  which 
must  be  lifted  in  lifting  the  bottom,  not  the  whole  vessel. 
This  seems  to  have  met  with  comprehension  at  once.  The 


234  THE  MONIST. 

ingenious  and  spontaneous  complacency  of  this  American 
was  altogether  charming  and  delightful  to  me.  He  an- 
swered me  in  English  since  he  knew  no  other  language. 
He  lived  in  "Cosmopolis" — street  and  number  were  un- 
necessary, simply  the  name  of  the  writer  sufficed.  Hence 
the  place  was  probably  not  yet  Cosmopolis,  but  for  the 
time  being  perhaps  an  embryo  of  five  or  ten  houses  which 
had  undertaken  to  become  a  cosmopolis. 

Intercourse  with  born  thinkers  of  this  type  is  very 
agreeable  to  me.  Thus  I  would  love  to  have  known  that 
naive  Chinaman  who,  pointing  to  the  street-car  in  San 
Francisco,  the  propelling  force  of  which  seemed  incom- 
prehensible to  him,  said  (as  my  colleague  B.  Brauner  tells 
me),  "No  pushee,  no  pullee,  but  it  runs — ." 


One  day  I  had  a  visitor  whose  external  appearance 
proclaimed  him  every  inch  a  man  conscious  of  successful 
achievement.  Without  any  doubt  he  was  also  intelligent, 
a  good  observer  who  had  used  his  own  eyes  and  knew  how 
to  turn  his  observations  to  practical  account.  He  belonged 
to  the  class  of  inventors  on  occasion  who  base  their  con- 
structions on  practical  and  local  knowledge  and  not  on  the 
fancy  that  something  must  be  invented  whether  or  no.  He 
certainly  deserved  the  success  of  his  great  business  which 
extended  over  all  Europe.  But  what  surprised  me  was 
that  he  manifested  such  high  theoretical  aims  at  the  same 
time.  He  felt  like  the  laboratory  assistant  of  Faraday 
who  performed  experiments  while  the  great  man  only 
delivered  the  superfluous  lecture  about  them.  How  could 
this  great  lecture,  called  science,  have  many  difficulties 
for  one  who  was  so  successful  in  his  practical  life,  for  that 
is  the  proof  of  the  sum?  Then  too  his  theory  was  not  in 
the  least  without  foundation,  for  it  rested  on  independent 
observation,  that  is  to  say,  on  what  is  called  the  Leiden- 


INVENTORS  I  HAVE  MET.  235 

frost  experiment.  But  while  he  ascribed  to  this  one  ob- 
servation an  unduly  enormous  significance,  he  questioned 
at  the  same  time  the  Newton  theory  of  gravitation  and  all 
other  possible  theories,  or  undertook  to  base  them  on  differ- 
ent foundations.  My  word  for  it,  his  observation  was 
good,  but  onesided  and  incomplete,  and  therefore  inade- 
quate for  a  foundation  of  his  theories  and  would  not  bear 
much  fruit.  He  had  a  strong  desire  to  rush  at  once  into 
print.  "If  you  wish  to  do  that,  my  dear  sir,  I  advise  you 
at  least  to  publish  anonymously  or  under  a  pseudonym. 
In  case  you  are  ridiculed  you  can  then  join  heartily  in  the 
laugh  without  anxiety  for  your  reputation."  The  sensible 
man  followed  this  advice  and  was  splendidly  successful  in 
his  book  selling,  for  there  are  plenty  of  imaginative  people 
who  take  pleasure  in  crazy  theories.  "Wisdom  and  ex- 
perience in  one  field/'  I  said  also  in  the  course  of  our  con- 
versation, "do  not  protect  us  from  folly  in  another.  You 
are  efficient  in  your  specialty  and  we  will  suppose  that  I 
am  in  mine.  Would  we  not  both  be  astonished  and  con- 
fused if  you  for  instance  would  come  out  to-morrow  as  an 
obstetrician  and  I  the  day  after  as  a  dentist  ?  And  yet  no 
less  schooling  and  experience  are  needed  for  the  conquest 
of  a  scientific  specialty." 


Many  people  feel  that  nothing  else  so  cramps  and  limits 
their  imagination  as  certain  principles  in  science  which 
are  held  to  be  firmly  established  and  which  others  are  used 
to  look  upon  as  providing  the  most  abundant  aid.  Such 
a  principle  for  instance  is  that  of  the  equality  of  action 
and  reaction,  and  another  is  that  of  the  impossibility  of 
perpetual  motion. 

Once  I  was  urgently  invited  to  visit  a  man  who  wished 
to  show  me  something  very  remarkable.  When  I  arrived 
he  first  told  me  the  following  story.  He  said  that  he  had 


236  THE  MONIST. 

never  doubted  the  principle  of  the  equality  of  pressure  and 
counter-pressure.  But  once  he  had  heard  a  traveler  tell 
of  an  animal  in  South  America  that  sprang  with  agility 
from  branch  to  branch  without  communicating  the  slightest 
motion  to  the  branches  either  as  it  left  one  or  reached  the 
the  other.  This  aroused  his  interest  so  greatly  that  he 
went  at  once  to  South  America  in  order  to  observe  this 
squirrel-like  animal.  Here  he  convinced  himself  that  the 
law  of  the  equality  of  pressure  and  counter-pressure  did 
not  hold  good.  Upon  his  return  he  succeeded  in  devising 
an  arrangement  with  which  by  means  of  cords  fastened 
to  one  and  the  same  body  a  motor  tendency  was  communi- 
cated to  this  body.  He  showed  me  a  ruler  in  which  a  motor 
impulse  would  arise  by  means  of  threads  crossed  and 
stretched  in  various  directions  between  swivels.  As  he 
held  it  in  his  hand  he  said,  "Now  I  feel  myself  drawn  over 
there  towards  the  door,"  whereupon  he  proceeded  to  step 
in  that  direction.  "If  that  is  so,  sir,"  answered  I,  "you 
will  easily  be  able  to  convince  every  one  of  the  fact,  if  you 
will  let  this  ruler  swim  freely  on  the  surface  of  water  so 
that  it  can  move  in  a  definite  direction  without  your  per- 
sonal intervention."  This  he  promised  to  do.  I  now  felt 
myself  impelled  toward  the  door  and  took  my  leave  as  I 
began  to  feel  somewhat  uncanny.  It  was  really  very  dis- 
quieting to  remain  in  a  place  where,  because  of  the  inequal- 
ity of  pressure  and  counter-pressure,  a  tied-up  package 
or  a  well-screwed  piece  of  furniture  would  be  able  spon- 
taneously and  independently  to  get  up  and  travel  and  fly 
at  my  head.  It  is  now  about  twenty  years  since  I  have 
heard  anything  of  this  wonderful  experiment. 


There  was  an  old  gentleman  of  whom  I  was  very  fond 
who  took  a  great  interest  in  the  problem  of  perpetual  mo- 
tion. He  held  that  an  instance  of  it  must  eventually  be 


INVENTORS  I  HAVE  MET. 


237 


found  because  it  was  necessary  for  the  progress  of  human- 
ity. The  most  diverse  hydraulic  and  mechanical  construc- 
tions were  undertaken.  When  they  were  complicated  enough 
so  that  they  could  not  be  seen  through  he  thought  he  had 
reached  his  goal,  but  each  time  was  of  course  disillusioned. 
Since  he  was  an  educated  man  I  gave  him  Huygens's 
Horologium  oscillatorium  to  read  in  which  these  condi- 
tions are  set  forth  very  clearly  and  simply,  but  it  made 
no  permanent  impression.  Ever  and  again  his  imagination 
overcame  his  judgment  and  ever  and  again  triumphed  the 


Fig.  i. 


Fig.  2. 


unshakable  conviction  of  the  necessity  of  this  thing  for  the 
good  of  humanity.  Somewhat  similarly  must  Aristotle 
have  thought  with  regard  to  the  displacing  of  slave  labor 
by  the  use  of  machinery. 

One  of  the  constructions  of  the  old  gentleman  I  remem- 
ber very  distinctly.  It  may  be  easily  understood  as  pre- 
sented in  Fig.  i.  A  siphon  ab  dips  into  the  vessel  A  and 
at  the  other  end  with  a  bell-shaped  expansion  C  into  the 
vessel  D.  If  the  openings  a  and  e  are  left  unobstructed 
then,  according  to  the  expectation  of  the  inventor,  the 


238  THE  MONIST. 

small  mass  of  water  in  the  tube  ab  would  follow  the  large 
masses  of  C  and  D  and  flow  out  at  e.  Instead  of  this,  Cba 
behaved  like  a  normal  siphon  flowing  in  the  direction  indi- 
cated by  the  letters,  whereas  a  part  of  the  water  in  D,  to 
be  sure,  descended  through  e  so  that  a  break  occurred 
between  the  water  in  C  and  in  D,  whereat  the  arrangement 
had  failed  to  perform  its  function. 

*  *       * 

When  I  was  a  boy  I  had  heard  so  much  about  perpetual 
motion  that  at  a  time  when  I  had  only  a  very  superficial 
knowledge  of  the  law  of  the  lever  I  zealously  set  to  work 
on  the  construction  of  a  perpetuum  mobile.  The  drawing 
in  Fig.  2  will  make  clear  the  construction  and  its  error. 
I  was  tempted  to  regard  the  horizontal  bars  with  weights 
as  somewhat  long  and  efficient  levers,  although  in  this 
case  there  could  be  no  question  of  levers  and  their  rota- 
tion. Nature  does  not  allow  itself  to  be  outwitted  like  the 
limited  attention  of  man.  To  lift  a  weight  P  to  the  height 
H  absolutely  requires  a  weight  P'  which  reaches  the  depth 
H',  so  that  P'XH'  is  at  least  equal  to  PXH.  I  can  not 
say  that  this  effort  did  me  any  harm.  The  mistake  taught 
me  to  understand  machines  better  than  books  or  instruction 
could  have  done.2  If  any  theory  is  of  practical  value  in 
promoting  civilization  it  is  that  of  the  limitation  of  avail- 
able mechanical  power,  and  no  illusion  is  more  harmful  to 
progress  than  the  idea  of  its  inexhaustibility.3 

*  *       * 

One  of  the  most  remarkable  inventors  whom  I  have 
ever  known  was  an  old  mechanic.  At  every  detail  he  noted 
some  advantage  in  construction  and  at  once  applied  his 
idea.  He  reformed  the  handles  and  shape  of  beer  glasses, 

3  The  collection  of  constructions  of  perpetual  motion  machines  preserved 
in  the  Technical  Museum  at  Munich  must  be  very  instructive  from  a  psycho- 
logical point  of  view,  as  far  as  they  can  be  deciphered. 

8  Indeed  one  of  the  greatest  advances  made  in  natural  science  rests  upon 
the  overthrow  of  this  illusion  through  a  fundamental  employment  of  it. 


INVENTORS  I   HAVE  MET.  239 

laundry  mangles,  theater  curtains ;  he  constructed  a  clock 
from  a  barometer-tube  closed  at  both  ends  in  which  a  short 
column  of  mercury  was  placed  at  the  side  of  a  scale  marked 
off  empirically  to  measure  time.  He  was  a  funny  old  fel- 
low who  wished  to  do  away  with  the  figures  on  the  tower 
clock  because  "anyone  would  be  a  fool  who  would  not  be 
able  to  tell  the  time  by  the  position  of  the  hands."  He 
was  a  born  physicist.  From  his  simple  story  I  can  not 
doubt  that  by  blowing  away  the  sawdust  from  a  circular 
saw  with  perforations  in  the  rim  he  discovered  of  his  own 
accord  the  principle  of  the  disk-shaped  siren  and  the  law 
of  tone  vibrations. 

He  was  as  extremely  jealous  of  Cagniard  Latour  as 
if  the  latter  by  his  much  earlier  observation  had  robbed  him 
of  the  finest  discovery.  On  the  principle  of  the  disk-siren 
he  based  his  invention  of  a  new  musical  instrument  which 
he  called  a  sirenophone.  By  means  of  a  weight  and  a  con- 
tinuous cord  a  pedal  set  the  system  of  the  siren-disks  in 
uniform  rotation  and  at  the  same  time  worked  a  bellows. 
Piano  keys,  sunk  more  or  less  deeply  with  increased  pres- 
sure, opened  one  or  more  tubes  which  blew  with  varying 
degrees  of  strength  into  the  series  of  holes  of  the  siren- 
disks  so  as  to  swell  individual  tones.  The  difference  in 
pitch  was  obtained  by  the  proportion  of  the  radii  of  the 
pulleys  over  which  the  cords  of  the  disks  were  drawn.  This 
instrument  made  far  more  pleasant  music  than  a  har- 
monium and  it  would  be  simply  impossible  for  it  to  get  out 
of  tune.  It  could  be  manufactured  in  perfect  tune  by  a 
simple  method  of  stamping.  When  a  young  man  proposed 
to  the  inventor  to  sell  his  invention  but  keep  its  name,  he 
received  the  answer,  "The  invention  is  great  but  unsa- 
lable." Hence  he  apparently  preferred  that  it  continue  its 
existence  as  unique  and  legendary  rather  than  be  a  source 
of  profit.  When  a  colleague  once  tried  to  play  the  instru- 
ment the  inventor  fell  upon  him  furiously  and  declared  it 


24O  THE  MONIST. 

was  a  sacrilege.  The  inventor  surrounded  himself  with 
the  mystery  of  a  medieval  wizard  and  conjurer.  The  orders 
of  the  minor  petty  German  princes  for  whom  he  had  ar- 
ranged various  theatrical  details  he  wore  with  ostentation 
and  listed  them  carefully  upon  his  visiting  cards.  This 
man's  vanity  greatly  diminished  the  impression  of  his  very 
considerable  talent  and  disturbed  his  relations  with  his 
hardly  less  gifted  brother. 


In  my  institute  I  once  had  a  very  gifted  young  man  D. 
to  whom  I  proposed  that  he  carry  on  a  piece  of  work  in 
physiological  optics  in  which  he  made  good  progress.  One 
day  I  came  to  him  with  the  question,  "Well,  what  are  you 
doing?"  "Nothing,"  was  the  answer,  "because  I  haven't 
any  pasteboard  to  make  a  new  disk."  "Well,  if  that  is  all 
it  takes  to  put  a  stop  to  your  research  you  will  not  get  very 
far,"  was  my  reply.  This  episode  would  not  have  remained 
in  my  memory  if  D.  had  not  reminded  me  of  it  years  later. 
But  it  is  noteworthy  that  soon  afterwards  he  completed 
a  series  of  fine  tasks  for  which  he  had  provided  himself 
with  all  necessary  devices  in  the  simplest  way  possible;  he 
almost  never  had  need  for  anything  from  the  materials 
of  the  institute.  He  constructed  a  Jamin  compensator  by 
cutting  a  slightly  curved  optical  lens.  I  must  add  that  I 
have  seen  many  similar  accessories  in  the  collection  left  by 
Norrenberg  in  Tubingen.  There  stood  whole  cases  full  of 
the  cleverest  optical  apparatus  made  out  of  cork  and  glass. 
Norrenberg  let  the  endowment  lapse  and  made  his  appa- 
ratus himself  in  order  not  to  have  to  write  everything  down 
in  the  inventory  book  and  keep  a  strict  account  of  it.  Every 
curator  of  an  institution  is  familiar  with  this  burden  which 
always  intrudes  upon  his  most  convenient  time  for  work,  or 
on  his  vacation. 

The  young  man  D.,  who  was  the  exact  opposite  of  the 


INVENTORS  I  HAVE  MET.  24! 

preceding  one  in  seriousness  and  simplicity,  soon  became 
my  assistant  and  left  with  me  a  cheerful  memory  of  his 
dry  humor.  When  I  was  demonstrating  to  beginners  the 
interference  bands  of  the  sodium  flame  by  the  greater 
thickness  of  layers  of  air  of  the  Newton  glass  and  bade 
them  not  to  focus  their  eyes  upon  the  flame  but  on  the 
glass,  they  did  not  all  succeed  in  this  at  once.  With  averted 
face  the  assistant  scattered  a  few  grains  of  salt  over  the 
glass,  with  the  words,  "There  now,  look  at  the  salt !"  When 
I  pointed  out  the  Talbot  bands  by  covering  half  of  the  pupil 
with  a  piece  of  mica  many  looked  through  the  mica  and 
many  looked  past  it.  The  assistant  cut  a  small  hole  in  a 
piece  of  black  paste  board  and  covered  the  half  with  mica, 
saying:  "There  now,  look  through  the  hole!"  When  I 
called  attention  to  the  range  of  oscillation  of  a  string  which 
vibrated  the  fundamental  tone  and  the  octave  at  the  same 
time,  one  of  the  class  was  almost  misled  into  considering 
it  two  strings.  "Put  your  finger  in  between  quick,  then 
you  will  have  two !"  said  the  assistant. 


In  this  brief  review  we  have  not  drawn  any  sharp  dis- 
tinction between  inventors  and  thinkers,  between  invention 
and  discovery.  Indeed  there  is  no  great  difference.  The 
liberation  from  a  practical  discomfort  by  a  new  procedure 
we  call  an  invention.  But  if  we  feel  an  intellectual  discom- 
fort, in  that  for  instance  we  can  not  follow  in  our  thought 
an  unaccustomed  fact  and  can  not  see  through  it,  then  we 
call  a  serviceable  guide  of  our  thoughts  which  helps  us  to 
do  so  a  discovery.  When  a  man  fiinds  he  can  not  boil 
water  in  a  pumpkin  shell  because  it  catches  fire  he  invents 
the  pot  by  surrounding  the  pumpkin  with  clay.  When  a 
man  can  not  understand  the  light  and  dark  bands  in  con- 
flicting rays  of  light  from  two  identical  sources  because  he 
thinks  of  light  as  a  uniform  stream  he  discovers  inter- 


242  THE  MONIST. 

ference  from  the  instruction  to  represent  light  with  period- 
ically changing  properties.  Discoveries  and  inventions  may 
be  due  to  an  accidental  occasional  observation,  as  is  shown 
in  the  above  examples.  In  other  cases  they  may  be  the 
result  of  prolonged  systematic  work  as  has  been  illumi- 
natingly  presented  by  the  Muscovite  engineer  P.  K.  v. 
Engelmeyer  in  his  essay  Der  Dreiakt  ah  Lehre  von  der 
Technik  und  der  Erfindung  (Berlin,  Heymann,  1910). 4 
If  an  invention  is  to  be  made  there  must  be  the  desire  to 
remove  an  inconvenience ;  there  must  be  the  knowledge  of 
the  means  by  which  this  can  be  done,  and  the  ability  to 
make  a  practical  application  of  them.  This  is  the  Dreiakt 
of  the  purpose,  the  plan  for  attaining  it  and  the  material 
performance  which  takes  place  mutatis  mutandis  also  when- 
ever a  theoretical  problem  is  put  to  a  practical  application. 

ERNST  MACH. 
VIENNA,  AUSTRIA. 

4  See  a  further  account  of  this  work  in  the  editorial  in  this  number  en- 
titled "A  New  Theory  of  Invention." 


THE  NEW  LOGICS.1 

I.  THE  RUSSELL  LOGIC. 

TO  justify  its  pretensions,  logic  had  to  change.  We 
have  seen  new  logics  arise  of  which  the  most  inter- 
esting is  that  of  Russell.  It  seems  he  has  nothing  new  to 
write  about  formal  logic,  as  if  Aristotle  there  had  touched 
bottom.  But  the  domain  Russell  attributes  to  logic  is  in- 
finitely more  extended  than  that  of  the  classic  logic,  and 
he  has  put  forth  on  the  subject  views  which  are  original 
and  at  times  well  warranted. 

First,  Russell  subordinates  the  logic  of  classes  to  that 
of  propositions,  while  the  logic  of  Aristotle  was  above  all 
the  logic  of  classes  and  took  as  its  point  of  departure  the 
relation  of  subject  to  predicate.  The  classic  syllogism, 
"Socrates  is  a  man,"  etc.,  gives  place  to  the  hypothetical 
syllogism:  "If  A  is  true,  B  is  true;  now  if  B  is  true,  C  is 
true/'  etc.  And  this  is,  I  think,  a  most  happy  idea,  be- 
cause the  classic  syllogism  is  easy  to  carry  back  to  the 
hypothetical  syllogism,  while  the  inverse  transformation 
is  not  without  difficulty. 

And  then  this  is  not  all.  Russell's  logic  of  propositions 
is  the  study  of  the  laws  of  combination  of  the  conjunctions 
if,  and,  or,  and  the  negation  not. 

In  adding  here  two  other  conjunctions  and  and  or, 
Russell  opens  to  logic  a  new  field.  The  symbols  and,  or 
follow  the  same  laws  as  the  two  signs  X  and  -f-,  that  is 

translated  by  George  Bruce  Halsted. 


244  THE  MONIST. 

to  say  the  commutative,  associative  and  distributive  laws. 
Thus  and  represents  logical  multiplication,  while  or  repre- 
sents logical  addition.  This  also  is  very  interesting. 

Russell  reaches  the  conclusion  that  any  false  proposi- 
tion implies  all  other  propositions  true  or  false.  M.  Cou- 
turat  says  this  conclusion  will  at  first  seem  paradoxical. 
It  is  sufficient  however  to  have  corrected  a  bad  thesis  in 
mathematics  to  recognize  how  right  Russell  is.  The  candi- 
date often  is  at  great  pains  to  get  the  first  false  equation; 
but  that  once  obtained,  it  is  only  sport  then  for  him  to  ac- 
cumulate the  most  surprising  results,  some  of  which  even 
may  be  true. 

ii. 

We  see  how  much  richer  the  new  logic  is  than  the 
classic  logic ;  the  symbols  are  multiplied  and  allow  of  varied 
combinations  which  are  no  longer  limited  in  number.  Has 
one  the  right  to  give  this  extension  to  the  meaning  of  the 
word  logic  ?  It  would  be  useless  to  examine  this  question 
and  to  seek  with  Russell  a  mere  quarrel  about  words. 
Grant  him  what  he  demands;  but  be  not  astonished  if 
certain  verities  declared  irreducible  to  logic  in  the  old 
sense  of  the  word  find  themselves  now  reducible  to  logic 
in  the  new  sense — something  very  different. 

A  great  number  of  new  notions  have  been  introduced, 
and  these  are  not  simply  combinations  of  the  old.  Russell 
knows  this,  and  not  only  at  the  beginning  of  the  first  chap- 
ter, "The  Logic  of  Propositions,"  but  at  the  beginning 
of  the  second  and  third,  "The  Logic  of  Classes"  and  "The 
Logic  of  Relations,"  he  introduces  new  words  that  he  de- 
clares indefinable. 

And  this  is  not  all;  he  likewise  introduces  principles 
he  declares  indemonstrable.  But  these  indemonstrable 
principles  are  appeals  to  intuition,  synthetic  judgments 
a  priori.  We  regard  them  as  intuitive  when  we  meet 


THE  NEW  LOGICS.  245 

them  more  or  less  explicitly  enunciated  in  mathematical 
treatises;  have  they  changed  character  because  the  mean- 
ing of  the  word  logic  has  been  enlarged  and  we  now  find 
them  in  a  book  entitled  "Treatise  on  Logic"?  They  have 
not  changed  nature;  they  have  only  changed  place. 

in. 

Could  these  principles  be  considered  as  disguised  defi- 
nitions ?  It  would  then  be  necessary  to  have  some  way  of 
proving  that  they  imply  no  contradiction.  It  would  be 
necessary  to  establish  that,  however  far  one  followed  the 
series  of  deductions,  he  would  never  be  exposed  to  contra- 
dicting himself. 

We  might  attempt  to  reason  as  follows :  We  can  verify 
that  the  operations  of  the  new  logic  applied  to  premises  ex- 
empt from  contradiction  can  only  give  consequences  equally 
exempt  from  contradiction.  If  therefore  after  n  opera- 
tions we  have  not  met  contradiction,  we  shall  not  encoun- 
ter it  after  n-fi.  Thus  it  is  impossible  that  there  should 
be  a  moment  when  contradiction  begins,  which  shows  we 
shall  never  meet  it.  Have  we  the  right  to  reason  in  this 
way?  No,  for  this  would  be  to  make  use  of  complete  in- 
duction ;  and  remember,  zve  do  not  yet  know  the  principle 
of  complete  induction. 

We  therefore  have  not  the  right  to  regard  these  as- 
sumptions as  disguised  definitions  and  only  one  resource 
remains  for  us,  to  admit  a  new  act  of  intuition  for  each 
of  them.  Moreover  I  believe  this  is  indeed  the  thought  of 
Russell  and  M.  Couturat. 

Thus  each  of  the  nine  indefinable  notions  and  of  the 
twenty  indemonstrable  propositions  (I  believe  if  it  were 
I  that  did  the  counting,  I  should  have  found  some  more) 
which  are  the  foundation  of  the  new  logic,  logic  in  the 
broad  sense,  presupposes  a  new  and  independent  act  of 
our  intuition  and  (why  not  say  it?)  a  veritable  synthetic 


246  THE  MONIST. 

judgment  a  priori.  On  this  point  all  seem  agreed,  but 
what  Russell  claims,  and  what  seems  to  me  doubtful,  is 
that  after  these  appeals  to  intuition,  that  will  be  the  end 
of  it;  we  need  make  no  others  and  can  build  all  mathemat- 
ics without  the  intervention  of  any  new  element. 

M.  Couturat  often  repeats  that  this  new  logic  is  alto- 
gether independent  of  the  idea  of  number.  I  shall  not 
amuse  myself  by  counting  how  many  numeral  adjectives  his 
exposition  contains,  both  cardinal  and  ordinal,  or  indefi- 
nite adjectives  such  as  several.  We  may  cite  however  some 
examples : 

"The  logical  product  of  two  or  more  propositions  is 

D  . 
....    , 

"All  propositions  are  capable  only  of  two  values,  true 
and  false"; 

"The  relative  product  of  two  relations  is  a  relation"; 

"A  relation  exists  between  two  terms,"  etc.,  etc. 

Sometimes  this  inconvenience  would  not  be  unavoid- 
able, but  sometimes  also  it  is  essential.  A  relation  is  in- 
comprehensible without  two  terms ;  it  is  impossible  to  have 
the  intuition  of  the  relation,  without  having  at  the  same 
time  that  of  its  two  terms,  and  without  noticing  they  are  two, 
because,  if  the  relation  is  to  be  conceivable,  it  is  necessary 
that  there  be  two  and  only  two. 

v. 

ARITHMETIC 

I  reach  what  M.  Couturat  calls  the  ordinal  theory  which 
is  the  foundation  of  arithmetic  properly  so  called.  M. 
Couturat  begins  by  stating  Peano's  five  assumptions,  which 
are  independent,  as  has  been  proved  by  Peano  and  Padoa. 

1.  Zero  is  an  integer. 

2.  Zero  is  not  the  successor  of  any  integer. 

3.  The  successor  of  an  integer  is  an  integer. 
To  this  it  would  be  proper  to  add, 


THE  NEW  LOGICS.  247 

Every  integer  has  a  successor. 

4.  Two  integers  are  equal  if  their  successors  are. 

The  fifth  assumption  is  the  principle  of  complete  induc- 
tion. 

M.  Couturat  considers  these  assumptions  as  disguised 
definitions;  they  constitute  the  definition  by  postulates  of 
zero,  of  successor,  and  of  integer. 

But  we  have  seen  that  for  a  definition  by  postulates  to 
be  acceptable  we  must  be  able  to  prove  that  it  implies  no 
contradiction. 

Is  this  the  case  here?     Not  at  all. 

The  demonstration  cannot  be  made  by  example.  We 
cannot  take  a  part  of  the  integers,  for  instance  the  first 
three,  and  prove  they  satisfy  the  definition. 

If  I  take  the  series  o,  i,  2,  I  see  it  fulfils  the  assump- 
tions i,  2,  4,  and  5;  but  to  satisfy  assumption  3,  it  still  is 
necessary  that  3  be  an  integer,  and  consequently  that  the 
series  o,  i,  2,  3,  fulfil  the  assumptions;  we  might  prove 
that  it  satisfies  assumptions  i,  2,  4,  5,  but  assumption  3 
requires  besides  that  4  be  an  integer  and  that  the  series 
o,  i,  2,  3,  4,  fulfil  the  assumptions,  and  so  on. 

It  is  therefore  impossible  to  demonstrate  the  assump- 
tions for  certain  integers  without  proving  them  for  all; 
we  must  give  up  proof  by  example. 

It  is  necessary  then  to  take  all  the  consequences  of  our 
assumptions  and  see  if  they  contain  no  contradiction. 

If  these  consequences  were  finite  in  number,  this  would 
be  easy;  but  they  are  infinite  in  number;  they  are  the 
whole  of  mathematics,  or  at  least  all  arithmetic. 

What  then  is  to  be  done?  Perhaps  strictly  we  could 
repeat  the  reasoning  of  number  III. 

But  as  we  have  said,  this  reasoning  is  complete  induc- 
tion, and  it  is  precisely  the  principle  of  complete  induction 
whose  justification  would  be  the  point  in  question. 


248  THE  MONIST. 

VI. 
THE  LOGIC  OF  HILBERT. 

I  come  now  to  the  capital  work  of  Hilbert  which  he 
communicated  to  the  Congress  of  Mathematicians  at  Hei- 
delberg, and  of  which  a  French  translation  by  M.  Pierre 
Boutroux  appeared  in  I'Enseignement  mathematique,  while 
an  English  translation  due  to  Halsted  appeared  in  The 
Monist.2  In  this  work,  which  contains  profound  thoughts, 
the  author's  aim  is  analogous  to  that  of  Russell,  but  on 
many  points  he  diverges  from  his  predecessor. 

"But/'  he  says  (Monist,  p.  340),  "on  attentive  con- 
sideration we  become  aware  that  in  the  usual  exposition 
of  the  laws  of  logic  certain  fundamental  concepts  of  arith- 
metic are  already  employed,  for  example  the  concept  of 
the  aggregate,  in  part  also  the  concept  of  number. 

"We  fall  thus  into  a  vicious  circle  and  therefore  to 
avoid  paradoxes  a  partly  simultaneous  development  of  the 
laws  of  logic  and  arithmetic  is  requisite." 

We  have  seen  above  that  what  Hilbert  says  of  the 
principles  of  logic  in  the  usual  exposition,  applies  likewise 
to  the  logic  of  Russell.  So  for  Russell  logic  is  prior  to 
arithmetic;  for  Hilbert  they  are  "simultaneous."  We  shall 
find  further  on  other  differences  still  greater,  but  we  shall 
point  them  out  as  we  come  to  them.  I  prefer  to  follow  step 
by  step  the  development  of  Hilbert's  thought,  quoting  tex- 
tually  the  most  important  passages. 

"Let  us  take  as  the  basis  of  our  consideration  first  of  all 
a  thought-thing  i  (one)"  (p.  341).  Notice  that  in  so  do- 
ing we  in  no  wise  imply  the  notion  of  number,  because  it 
is  understood  that  i  is  here  only  a  symbol  and  that  we  do 
not  at  all  seek  to  know  its  meaning.  "The  taking  of  this 
thing  together  with  itself  respectively  two,  three  or  more 
times .  . .  . "  Ah !  this  time  it  is  no  longer  the  same ;  if  we 

"The  Foundations  of  Logic  and  Arithmetic,"  Monist  XV,  338-352. 


THE  NEW  LOGICS.  249 

introduce  the  words  "two,"  "three,"  and  above  all  "more," 
"several,"  we  introduce  the  notion  of  number;  and  then 
the  definition  of  finite  whole  number  which  we  shall  pres- 
ently find,  will  come  too  late.  Our  author  was  too  circum- 
spect not  to  perceive  this  begging  of  the  question.  So  at 
the  end  of  his  work  he  tries  to  proceed  to  a  truly  patching 
up  process. 

Hilbert  then  introduces  two  simple  objects  I  and  =, 
and  considers  all  the  combinations  of  these  two  objects,  all 
the  combinations  of  their  combinations,  etc.  It  goes  with- 
out saying  that  we  must  forget  the  ordinary  meaning  of 
these  two  signs  and  not  attribute  any  to  them. 

Afterwards  he  separates  these  combinations  into  two 
classes,  the  class  of  the  existent  and  the  class  of  the  non- 
existent, and  till  further  orders  this  separation  is  entirely 
arbitrary.  Every  affirmative  statement  tells  us  that  a  cer- 
tain combination  belongs  to  the  class  of  the  existent ;  every 
negative  statement  tells  us  that  a  certain  combination  be- 
longs to  the  class  of  the  non-existent. 

IV. 

Note  now  a  difference  of  the  highest  importance.  For 
Russell  any  object  whatsoever,  which  he  designates  by  x, 
is  an  object  absolutely  undetermined  and  about  which  he 
supposes  nothing ;  for  Hilbert  it  is  one  of  the  combinations 
formed  with  the  symbols  i  and  =;  he  could  not  conceive 
of  the  introduction  of  any  thing  other  than  combinations 
of  objects  already  defined.  Moreover  Hilbert  formulates 
his  thought  in  the  neatest  way,  and  I  think  I  must  repro- 
duce in  extenso  his  statement  (p.  348)  : 

"In  the  assumptions  the  arbitraries  (as  equivalent  for 
the  concept  'every'  and  'air  in  the  customary  logic)  repre- 
sent only  those  thought-things  and  their  combinations  with 
one  another,  which  at  this  stage  are  laid  down  as  funda- 
mental or  are  to  be  newly  defined.  Therefore  in  the  deduc- 


25O  THE  MONIST. 

tion  of  inferences  from  the  assumptions,  the  arbitraries, 
which  occur  in  the  assumptions,  can  be  replaced  only  by 
such  thought-things  and  their  combinations. 

"Also  we  must  duly  remember,  that  through  the  super- 
addition  and  making  fundamental  of  a  new  thought-thing 
the  preceding  assumptions  undergo  an  enlargement  of 
their  validity,  and  where  necessary,  are  to  be  subjected  to 
a  change  in  conformity  with  the  sense." 

The  contrast  with  Russell's  view-point  is  complete.  For 
this  philosopher  we  may  substitute  for  x  not  only  objects 
already  known  but  any  thing. 

Russell  is  faithful  to  his  point  of  view,  which  is  that 
of  comprehension.  He  starts  from  the  general  idea  of 
being,  and  enriches  it  more  and  more  while  restricting 
it,  by  adding  new  qualities.  Hilbert  on  the  contrary  recog- 
nizes as  possible  beings  only  combinations  of  objects  al- 
ready known;  so  that  (looking  at  only  one  side  of  his 
thought)  we  might  say  he  takes  the  view-point  of  exten- 
sion. 

VIII. 

Let  us  continue  with  the  exposition  of  Hilbert's  ideas. 
He  introduces  two  assumptions  which  he  states  in  his  sym- 
bolic language  but  which  signify,  in  the  language  of  the 
uninitiated,  that  every  quantity  is  equal  to  itself  and  that 
every  operation  performed  upon  two  identical  quantities 
gives  identical  results. 

So  stated,  they  are  evident,  but  thus  to  present  them 
would  be  to  misrepresent  Hilbert's  thought.  For  him 
mathematics  have  to  combine  only  pure  symbols,  and  a 
true  mathematician  should  reason  upon  them  without  pre- 
conceptions as  to  their  meaning.  So  his  assumptions  are 
not  for  him  what  they  are  for  the  common  people. 

He  considers  them  as  representing  the  definition  by 
postulates  of  the  symbol  (=)  heretofore  void  of  all  sig- 


THE  NEW  LOGICS.  251 

nification.  But  to  justify  this  definition  we  must  show  that 
these  two  assumptions  lead  to  no  contradiction.  For  this 
Hilbert  used  the  reasoning  of  our  number  III,  without 
appearing  to  perceive  that  he  is  using  complete  induction. 

IX. 

The  end  of  Hilbert's  memoir  is  altogether  enigmatic 
and  I  shall  not  lay  stress  upon  it.  Contradictions  accumu- 
late; we  feel  that  the  author  is  dimly  conscious  of  the 
petitio  principii  he  has  committed,  and  that  he  seeks  vainly 
to  patch  up  the  holes  in  his  argument. 

What  does  this  mean?  At  the  point  of  proving  that 
the  definition  of  the  whole  number  by  the  assumption  of 
complete  induction  implies  no  contradiction,  Hilbert  with- 
draws as  Russell  and  Couturat  withdrew,  because  the  diffi- 
culty is  too  great. 

x. 

GEOMETRY. 

Geometry,  says  M.  Couturat,  is  a  vast  body  of  doctrine 
wherein  the  principle  of  complete  induction  does  not  enter. 
That  is  true  in  a  certain  measure;  we  cannot  say  it  is  en- 
tirely absent,  but  it  enters  very  slightly.  If  we  refer  to 
the  Rational  Geometry  of  Dr.  Halsted  (New  York,  John 
Wiley  and  Sons,  1904)  built  up  in  accordance  with  the 
principles  of  Hilbert,  we  see  the  principle  of  induction 
enter  for  the  first  time  on  page  114  (unless  I  have  made 
an  oversight,  which  is  quite  possible).3 

So  geometry  which  only  a  few  years  ago  seemed  the 
domain  where  the  reign  of  intuition  was  uncontested  is 
to-day  the  realm  where  the  logicians  seem  to  triumph. 
Nothing  could  better  measure  the  importance  of  the  geo- 
metric works  of  Hilbert  and  the  profound  impress  they 
have  left  on  our  conceptions. 

*2d.  ed,  1907,  p.  86;  French  ed.  1911,  p.  97.  G.  B.  H. 


252  THE  MONIST. 

But  be  not  deceived.  What  is  after  all  the  fundamental 
theorem  of  geometry?  It  is  that  the  assumptions  of  geom- 
etry imply  no  contradiction,  and  this  we  can  not  prove 
without  the  principle  of  induction. 

How  does  Hilbert  demonstrate  this  essential  point  ?  By 
leaning  upon  analysis  and  through  it  upon  arithmetic  and 
through  it  upon  the  principle  of  induction. 

And  if  ever  one  invents  another  demonstration,  it  will 
still  be  necessary  to  lean  upon  this  principle,  since  the  pos- 
sible consequences  of  the  assumptions,  of  which  it  is  neces- 
sary to  show  that  they  are  not  contradictory,  are  infinite 
in  number. 

XI. 

CONCLUSION. 

Our  conclusion  straightway  is  that  the  principle  of  in- 
duction cannot  be  regarded  as  the  disguised  definition  of 
the  entire  world. 

Here  are  three  truths :  ( i )  The  principle  of  complete 
induction;  (2)  Euclid's  postulate;  (3)  The  physical  law 
according  to  which  phosphorus  melts  at  44°  (cited  by  M. 
Le  Roy). 

These  are  said  to  be  three  disguised  definitions:  the 
first,  that  of  the  whole  number;  the  second,  that  of  the 
straight  line;  the  third,  that  of  phosphorus. 

I  grant  it  for  the  second;  I  do  not  admit  it  for  the 
other  two.  I  must  explain  the  reason  for  this  apparent 
inconsistency. 

First,  we  have  seen  that  a  definition  is  acceptable  only 
on  condition  that  it  implies  no  contradiction.  We  have 
shown  likewise  that  for  the  first  definition  this  demonstra- 
tion is  impossible;  on  the  other  hand  we  have  just  recalled 
that  for  the  second  Hilbert  has  given  a  complete  proof. 

As  to  the  third,  evidently  it  implies  no  contradiction. 
Does  this  mean  that  the  definition  guarantees,  as  it  should, 


THE  NEW  LOGICS.  253 

the  existence  of  the  object  defined  ?  We  are  here  no  longer 
in  the  mathematical  sciences,  but  in  the  physical,  and  the 
word  existence  has  no  longer  the  same  meaning.  It  no 
longer  signifies  absence  of  contradiction;  it  means  objec- 
tive existence. 

You  already  see  a  first  reason  for  the  distinction  I  made 
between  the  three  cases;  there  is  a  second.  In  the  appli- 
cations we  have  to  make  of  these  three  concepts,  do  they 
present  themselves  to  us  as  defined  by  these  three  postu- 
lates? 

The  possible  applications  of  the  principle  of  induction 
are  innumerable;  take  for  example  one  of  those  we  have 
expounded  above,  and  where  it  is  sought  to  prove  that  an 
aggregate  of  assumptions  can  lead  to  no  contradiction.  For 
this  we  consider  one  of  the  series  of  syllogisms  we  may  go 
on  with  in  starting  from  these  assumptions  as  premises. 
When  we  have  finished  the  nth  syllogism,  we  see  we  can 
make  still  another  and  this  is  the  n+ith.  Thus  the  num- 
ber n  serves  to  count  a  series  of  successive  operations;  it 
is  a  number  obtainable  by  successive  additions.  This  there- 
fore is  a  number  from  which  we  may  go  back  to  unity  by 
successive  subtractions.  Evidently  we  could  not  do  this 
if  we  had  n=n — i,  since  then  by  subtraction  we  should 
always  obtain  again  the  same  number.  So  the  way  we 
have  been  led  to  consider  this  number  n  implies  a  definition 
of  the  finite  whole  number  and  this  definition  is  the  follow- 
ing: A  finite  whole  number  is  that  which  can  be  obtained 
by  successive  additions;  it  is  such  that  n  is  not  equal  to 
n — I. 

That  granted,  what  do  we  do  ?  We  show  that  if  there 
has  been  no  contradiction  up  to  the  nth  syllogism,  no  more 
will  there  be  up  to  the  n-f-ith,  and  we  conclude  there  never 
will  be.  You  say:  I  have  the  right  to  draw  this  conclu- 
sion, since  the  whole  numbers  are  by  definition  those  for 
which  a  like  reasoning  is  legitimate.  But  that  implies 


254  THE  MONIST. 

another  definition  of  the  whole  number,  which  is  as  fol- 
lows :  A  whole  number  is  that  on  which  we  may  reason  by 
recurrence.  In  the  particular  case  it  is  that  of  which  we 
may  say  that,  if  the  absence  of  contradiction  up  to  the  time 
of  a  syllogism  of  which  the  number  is  an  integer  carries 
with  it  the  absence  of  contradiction  up  to  the  time  of  the 
syllogism  whose  number  is  the  following  integer,  we  need 
fear  no  contradiction  for  any  of  the  syllogisms  whose  num- 
ber is  an  integer. 

The  two  definitions  are  not  identical;  they  are  doubt- 
less equivalent,  but  only  in  virtue  of  a  synthetic  judgment 
a  priori]  we  cannot  pass  from  one  to  the  other  by  a  purely 
logical  procedure.  Consequently  we  have  no  right  to  adopt 
the  second,  after  having  introduced  the  whole  number  by 
a  way  that  presupposes  the  first. 

On  the  other  hand,  what  happens  with  regard  to  the 
straight  line?  I  have  already  explained  this  so  often  that 
I  hesitate  to  repeat  it  again,  and  shall  confine  myself  to  a 
brief  recapitulation  of  my  thought.  We  have  not,  as  in 
the  preceding  case,  two  equivalent  definitions  logically  ir- 
reducible one  to  the  other.  We  have  only  one  expressible 
in  words.  Will  it  be  said  there  is  another  which  we  feel 
without  being  able  to  word  it,  since  we  have  the  intuition 
of  the  straight  line  or  since  we  represent  to  ourselves  the 
straight  line?  First  of  all,  we  cannot  represent  it  to  our- 
selves in  geometric  space,  but  only  in  representative  space, 
and  then  we  can  represent  to  ourselves  just  as  well  the 
objects  which  possess  the  other  properties  of  the  straight 
line,  save  that  of  satisfying  Euclid's  postulate.  These  ob- 
jects are  "the  non- Euclidean  straights,"  which  from  a  cer- 
tain point  of  view  are  not  entities  void  of  sense  but  circles 
(true  circles  of  true  space)  orthogonal  to  a  certain  sphere. 
If,  among  these  objects  equally  capable  of  representation, 
it  is  the  first  (the  Euclidean  straights)  which  we  call 


THE  NEW  LOGICS.  255 

straights,  and  not  the  latter  (the  non-Euclidean  straights), 
this  is  properly  by  definition. 

And  arriving  finally  at  the  third  example,  the  definition 
of  phosphorus,  we  see  the  true  definition  would  be:  Phos- 
phorus is  the  bit  of  matter  I  see  in  yonder  flask. 

And  since  I  am  on  this  subject,  still  another  word.  Of 
the  phosphorus  example  I  said:  "This  proposition  is  a 
real  verifiable  physical  law,  because  it  means  that  all  bodies 
having  all  the  other  properties  of  phosphorus,  save  its 
point  of  fusion,  melt  like  it  at  44°."  And  it  was  answered : 
"No,  this  law  is  not  verifiable,  because  if  it  were  shown 
that  two  bodies  resembling  phosphorus  melt  one  at  44°  and 
the  other  at  50°,  it  might  always  be  said  that  doubtless,  be- 
sides the  point  of  fusion,  there  is  some  other  unknown 
property  by  which  they  differ." 

That  was  not  quite  what  I  meant  to  say.  I  should  have 
written,  "All  bodies  possessing  such  and  such  properties 
finite  in  number  (to  wit,  the  properties  of  phosphorus  stated 
in  the  books  on  chemistry,  the  fusion-point  excepted)  melt 
at  44°-" 

And  the  better  to  make  evident  the  difference  between 
the  case  of  the  straight  and  that  of  phosphorus,  one  more 
remark.  The  straight  has  in  nature  many  images  more  or 
less  imperfect,  of  which  the  chief  are  the  light  rays  and 
the  rotation  axis  of  the  solid.  Suppose  we  find  the  ray  of 
light  does  not  satisfy  Euclid's  postulate  (for  example  by 
showing  that  a  star  has  a  negative  parallax),  what  shall 
we  do  ?  Shall  we  conclude  that  the  straight  being  by  defi- 
nition the  trajectory  of  light  does  not  satisfy  the  postulate, 
or  on  the  other  hand  that  the  straight  by  definition  satis- 
fying the  postulate,  the  ray  of  light  is  not  straight? 

Assuredly  we  are  free  to  adopt  the  one  or  the  other 
definition  and  consequently  the  one  or  the  other  conclusion ; 
but  to  adopt  the  first  would  be  stupid,  because  the  ray  of 
light  probably  satisfies  only  imperfectly  not  merely  Euclid's 


256  THE  MONIST. 

postulate  but  the  other  properties  of  the  straight  line,  so 
that  if  it  deviates  from  the  Euclidean  straight,  it  deviates 
no  less  from  the  rotation  axis  of  solids  which  is  another 
imperfect  image  of  the  straight  line;  while  finally  it  is 
doubtless  subject  to  change,  so  that  such  a  line  which 
yesterday  was  straight  will  cease  to  be  straight  to-morrow 
if  some  physical  circumstance  has  changed. 

Suppose  now  we  find  that  phosphorus  does  not  melt 
at  44°,  but  at  43.9°.  Shall  we  conclude  that  phosphorus 
being  by  definition  that  which  melts  at  44°,  this  body  that 
we  did  call  phosporus  is  not  true  phosphorus,  or  on  the 
other  hand  that  phosphorus  melts  at  43.9°?  Here  again 
we  are  free  to  adopt  the  one  or  the  other  definition  and 
consequently  the  one  or  the  other  conclusion ;  but  to  adopt 
the  first  would  be  stupid  because  we  cannot  be  changing 
the  name  of  a  substance  every  time  we  determine  a  new 
decimal  of  its  fusion-point. 

XIII. 

To  sum  up,  Russell  and  Hilbert  have  each  made  a 
vigorous  effort;  they  have  each  written  a  work  full  of 
original  views,  profound  and  often  well  warranted.  These 
two  works  give  us  much  to  think  about  and  we  have  much 
to  learn  from  them.  Among  their  results,  some,  many 
even,  are  solid  and  destined  to  live. 

But  to  say  that  they  have  finally  settled  the  debate 
between  Kant  and  Leibnitz  and  ruined  the  Kantian  theory 
of  mathematics  is  evidently  incorrect.  I  do  not  know 
whether  they  really  believed  they  had  done  it,  but  if  they 
believed  so,  they  deceived  themselves. 

H.  POINCARE. 

PARIS,  FRANCE. 


THE  WEIRD  OF  LOVE  AND  DEATH. 


"O  inhabitant  of  Lebanon,  that  makest  thy  nest 
in  the  cedars,  how  gracious  shalt  thou  be  when 
pangs  come  upon  thee,  the  pain  as  of  a  woman 
in  travail." — Jeremiah,  xxii.  23. 

"Then  he  brought  me  to  the  door  of  the  gate  of 
the  Lord's  house,  which  was  toward  the  north; 
and  behold,  there  sat  women  weeping  for  Tam- 
muz." — Ezekiel,  viii.  14. 

"And  there  followed  him  a  great  company  of 
people,  and  of  women,  which  also  bewailed  and 
lamented  him. 

"But  Jesus  turning  unto  them  said,  Daughters 
of  Jerusalem,  weep  not  for  me,  but  weep  for 
yourselves  and  for  your  children. 

"For,  behold,  the  days  are  coming,  in  which 
they  shall  say,  Blessed  are  the  barren,  and  the 
wombs  that  never  bare,  and  the  paps  which  never 
gave  suck." — St.  Luke,  xxiii.  27,  28. 

The  author  of  the  following  verses  makes  no  claim  to  be  a 
translator,  but  merely  an  interpreter  of  a  chapter  from  the  Brick 
Bible  of  Babylon.  He  has  relied  upon  the  scholarship  of  others  for 
his  letter,  but  has  sought  its  spirit  not  only  beneath  the  text,  but  in 
the  actual  world  of  love  and  death.  Special  students  of  comparative 
religions  indeed  know  the  truth  of  Shakespeare's  59th  sonnet: 

"If  there  be  nothing  new,  but  that  which  is 
Hath  been  before,  how  are  our  brains  beguiled, 
Which,  laboring  for  invention,  bear  amiss 
The  second  burthen  of  a  former  child!" 


258  THE  MONIST. 

But  the  author  has  seen  no  other  English  version,  in  poetic  form,  of 
this  oldest  Semitic  Gospel  of  the  Resurrection,  which,  however  old 
it  be,  is  itself  a  translation,  like  the  Greek  Christian  Gospels,  from 
earlier  originals.1  Adonis  has  his  Greek  Gospels  also,  but  only  the 
apocryphal  have  come  down  to  us,  and  these  have  found  ample  em- 
bodiment in  Shakespeare's  "Venus  and  Adonis." 

The  author  has  welded  to  the  story  of  the  Descent  of  Istar,  two 
fragmentary  hymns  from  the  same  literature  invoking  the  Divine 
Pair,  which  common  invocation  is  confirmed  by  the  passage  of 
Jeremiah  (xxii.  18)  whose  Hebrew  text  should  read,  according  to 
Prof.  T.  K.  Cheyne :  "Alas,  my  Brother,  alas,  my  Sister !  Alas,  Adon, 
[Lord]  alas  Dodah!  [Beloved  Lady:  a  title  of  Istar]." 

The  cult  of  Dumu-zi-abzu  (Sumerian  or  Akkadian  "True  Son 
of  the  Deep  Water")  whom  the  Hebrews  alternately  adored  and  ab- 
horred as  Tammuz,  took,  in  its  migration  from  the  shore  of  the  Per- 
sian Gulf  to  the  ^Egean  and  Sicilian  coasts,  only  his  Semitic  title 
of  "Adon."  But  in  the  course  of  transit  the  divinity  first  became 
obscured  and  then  the  human  reputation.  From  a  benign  and  mys- 
terious power  behind  the  process  of  spring,  or  a  general  symbol  of 
the  life  principle  of  which  winter  deprives  nature  and  death  bereaves 
love,  he  became  a  demi-godlike  huntsman  and  paramour  of  Aphro- 
dite the  goddess  of  beauty.  Finally,  in  modern  parlance,  his  epithet 
has  dwindled  to  signify  a  pretty  youth.  Though  coming  from  further 
east,  the  worship  of  Tammuz  had  its  most  famous  seat  at  Aphaca 
(now  Afka)  about  fifteen  miles  from  the  Phenician  coast  near  the 
source  of  a  torrent  now  called  Ibrahim.  In  that  ravine  a  crude  but 
grand  cosmic  hypothesis  was  narrowed  to  a  vulgar  superstition.  The 
site  became  a  pagan  Loretto  or  Lourdes,  and  developed  a  perverse 
traffic  in  sacred  things  which  gave  to  Constantinople  in  the  fourth 
Christian  century  the  same  reason  or  pretext  for  suppression  that 
English  shrines  in  the  sixteenth  century  afforded  Henry  VIII. 

The  swift  stream  was  miraculously  tinged  each  year  with  the 
blood  of  the  dying  god  whose  title  it  then  bore.  It  is  said  that  the 
same  geologic  conditions  stll  perform  the  annual  miracle.  In  the 
Vale  of  Aphaca  the  triumph  as  well  as  the  agony  of  a  divine  victim 
were  localized,  just  as  later  they  were  at  Jerusalem.  From  Aphaca 
to  Galilee  it  is  but  eighty  miles  by  crow-flight,  and  to  Nazareth  less 

1Dr.  Alfred  Jeremias  has  published  the  original  text  of  the  Descent  of 
Istar  with  a  literal  German  translation.  An  English  version  founded  on  Dr. 
Jeremias's  translation,  appeared  in  The  Open  Court.  See  Cams,  "Babylonian 
and  Hebrew  Views  of  Man's  Fate  After  Death,"  XV,  p.  357. 


THE  WEIRD  OF  LOVE  AND  DEATH.  259 

than  one  hundred.  Indeed,  at  Bethlehem  (the  "House  of  Bread") 
which  lies  seventy  miles  further  south,  the  adoration  of  Tammuz, 
as  an  earlier  fruit  of  the  wheat  than  the  Christian  eucharist  wafer, 
lingered  in  the  days  of  St.  Jerome.  Though  an  enormous  ethical  dis- 
tance separates  the  personality  of  Jesus  from  the  mythical  boar- 
chaser  of  Lebanon,  the  dogmas  of  Chaldea  show  that  the  traditions 
of  the  church  rest  on  more  than  one  foundation.  The  Egyptian 
Gospel  of  Osiris  is  another  corner-stone. 

The  modest  figure  of  the  Virgin  Mother  Mary  has  little  in 
common  with  the  proud  and  passionate  image  of  Istar,  Ashtaroth  or 
Astarte.  Rather  has  the  concept  of  her  borrowed  the  attributes  of 
the  gracious  Egyptian  Isis.  Istar's  exchange  of  curses  with  her  in- 
fernal sister,  as  told  in  clay,  may  nevertheless  have  stirred  the  re- 
ligious feelings  of  her  votaries  among  the  fish-wives  of  Babylon. 
But  there  remains  something  in  the  grief  of  the  divine  bride  for  her 
lost  bridegroom  which  forecasts  the  plastic  pathos  of  Michelangelo's 
"Pieta"  and  is  echoed  in  the  rich  harmonies  of  Rossini's  "Stabat 
Mater  Dolorosa." 


To  realm  whence  no  echo  is  borne, 

to  region  no  pioneer  showeth; 
To  the  Castle  of  Darkness  Substantial, 

to  Yesterday's  shadowy  shore, 
Our  Lady  Astarte,  whose  beacon 

for  lovers  and  mariners  gloweth 
At  morning  and  even,  descended 

and  smote  on  the  dust-laden  door. 

"Now  open  the  gate  unto  me, 

grim  warden  that  keepest  the  marches! 
I  would  enter  the  Kingdom  of  Death !" 

cried  Our  Lady,  the  mystical  Bride. 
"Unless  to  my  summons  thou  hearken, 

thy  gate  I  will  rend  from  its  arches, 
Setting  free  to  outnumber  the  living, 

the  spirits  of  men  that  have  died !" 


26O  THE  MONIST. 

To  Lady  Astarte,  the  warden 

that  watcheth  the  entrance  of  Hades 
Made  reply:  "Till  I  take  to  my  mistress 

thy  word,  prithee,  Istar,  forbear!" 
(A  feud  for  eternity  lay 

'twixt  the  lovely  and  terrible  ladies, 
So  how  should  Death  bid  Love  be  welcome, 

and  ope  to  a  rival  her  lair?) 

To  pitiless  Queen  of  Irkalla 

the  seneschal  doubtfully  wended: 
"Sov'reign  Lady  of  Death,  at  the  precinct 

thy  sister  Astarte  doth  stand. 
Methinks  that  in  quest  of  the  life-giving 

water  the  Queen  hath  descended; 
The  bars  of  thy  mansion  are  shaken 

beneath  her  imperious  hand/' 

To  him  said  Queen  Allat:  "O  warden, 

as  grain  from  the  scythe  of  a  reaper 
To  the  Dungeon  of  Dust  falleth  Istar 

imploring  the  water  of  life! 
Like  lip  of  reed  that  is  thirsty 

her  need  is  for  Tammuz  the  Sleeper : 
But  what  are  her  sorrow  and  yearning 

to  us,  or  her  menace  of  strife? 

"Quoth  she:  'For  the  hero  I  mourn 

that  hath  left  his  wife  widow'd  and  lonely. 
I  lament  for  the  bride  whose  embraces 

her  husband  hath  lost  and  deplored; 
For  fate  of  the  innocent  children 

whose  span  bore  the  spring-blossom  only; 
So  lend  me  the  water  of  life, 

For  the  healing  of  Tammuz  my  Lord!' 


THE  WEIRD  OF  LOVE  AND  DEATH.  26l 

"Yet,  warden,  we  grant  her  caprice! 

Suffer  Istar  to  enter  our  portal 
In  conformity  strict  to  the  letter 

of  Death's  incompassionate  law. 
Deprive  her  of  every  adornment 

as  if  she  were  humble  and  mortal; 
Extinguish  the  glory  of  Istar 

that  filleth  the  heavens  with  awe!" 

The  warden  returning,  threw  open 

the  porch  of  Irkalla  to  Istar. 
"Thou  art  welcome  to  Death,  O  dread  Lady! 

Let  Ghostland  rejoice  in  its  guest! 
'T  is  mine  to  conduct  thee,  O  Queen, 

to  the  presence  of  Allat,  thy  sister!" 
But  as  she  stepp'd  over  the  threshold 

he  plucked  from  her  forehead  the  crest. 

"My  crown  with  the  crescent  and  star 

give  back  to  me!"  Istar  besought  him. 
"Nay,  my  Princess,  the  code  of  the  kingdom 

of  Death  even  thou  must  obey!" 
Through  Second  Gate  when  they  immerged, 

as  the  ruler  of  Hades  had  taught  him, 
The  warden  of  gloom  took  from  Istar 

The  radiant  ear-rings  away. 

And  so  at  each  barrier  passed, 

the  Queen  of  her  robe  he  divested, 
And  the  necklace,  the  brooch  and  the  belt 

and  the  bracelets  he  claim'd  as  his  prey. 
Relentless  and  brutal  he  was; 

When  Our  Lady  Astarte  protested, 
Repeating:  "Nay,  Princess,  the  edict 

of  Death  even  thou  must  obey!" 


262  THE  MONIST. 

So  into  the  hall  of  the  hopeless, 

the  court  of  Queen  Allat  the  Dreary, 
All  dishevelled,  discrowned  and  dismantled 

Our  Lady  Astarte  he  led. 
Though  her  aspect  was  that  of  despair, 

for  her  trials  were  many  and  weary, 
Not  dumb  was  Our  Lady  at  sight 

of  the  sinister  Queen  of  the  Dead. 

She  cursed  her  with  formula  dire, 

with  a  torrent  of  bitter  invective, 
And  she  wept  more  in  rage  than  in  sorrow, 

recounting  the  insults  of  Death. 
The  face  of  the  monarch  of  Hades 

grew  scornfully  sweet  and  reflective, 
Nor  uttered  she  one  interruption 

till  Istar  expended  her  breath, 

Then  spake  with  a  delicate  malice 

these  ominous  words  unto  Istar: 
"Since  thou  quittest  the  world,  not  a  beast 

of  the  wilderness  seeketh  a  mate, 
Nor  egg  hath  been  hatched  by  a  fowl, 

O  gentle  and  courteous  sister 
Who  threat'nest  my  realm  with  invasion, 

but  leavest  thine  own  desolate! 

"The  maids  of  the  men  are  unconscious, 

no  men  to  the  maids  make  advances; 
And  the  cradles  are  empty  and  rock'd 

by  the  hands  of  no  mothers  to-day; 
Their  music  the  forests  have  lost, 

the  cities  are  stilled  of  their  dances; 
The  land  of  the  living  is  stagnant 

since  Istar  to  Death  came  away. 


THE  WEIRD  OF  LOVE  AND  DEATH.  263 

"My  thralls  thou  hast  sought  to  suborn, 

by  promising  thou  wdiildst  deliver 
From  the  dust  of  the  grave  to  adore  thee 

again  on  thy  double-horned  throne — 
In  truth,  O  Astarte,  it  seemeth, 

now  Love  hath  discarded  her  quiver, 
The  task  would  be  light  for  annexing 

the  Kingdom  of  Life  to  mine  own! 

"Ho,  Namtar!  Take  Istar  and  plague  her 

with  sixty-fold  measure  of  illness! 
Assail  her  with  chastening  agues 

and  darken  the  flame  of  her  eyes! 
Let  agony  reign  in  her  bosom, 

her  ears  have  the  horror  of  stillness! 
Let  clouds  gather  over  her  spirit! 

Let  languor  her  limbs  paralyse!" 

Through  creation  there  mounted  a  shudder 

to  throne  of  the  Father  Eternal; 
To  the  One  whose  dominion  is  screened 

by  the  awful  illusion  of  space. 
All  nature  cried  out  at  the  tyranny 

seized  by  the  power  infernal; 
In  conclave  aghast  at  the  rumor 

the  sons  of  God  each  took  his  place. 

'T  is  June,  but  the  leafage  hath  fallen; 

't  is  summer,  but  rime  crusteth  over 
All  the  meads  of  the  planets  with  whiteness; 

't  is  season  for  rain,  but  a  drought 
The  field  of  ephemeral  life 

with  a  brown  desolation  doth  cover; 
The  fire  of  Astarte  is  dim; 

from  the  tomb  cometh  Tammuz  not  out!" 


264  THE  MONIST. 

So  Papsukal,  angel  of  light, 

unto  Mardttk  the  Sun-god  repeated, 
Who  arose  and  went  up  to  his  Father 

and  bowed  in  the  Presence  with  tears. 
The  lord  of  the  hours  for  grace 

of  the  Infinite  Spirit  entreated 
To  call  back  Our  Lady  Astarte 

from  Death  to  her  place  in  the  spheres. 

From  mind  of  the  Father  Eternal 

in  likeness  not  man  nor  yet  woman, 
Did  a  messenger  come  to  creation, 

with  countenance  fair  and  serene. 
By  myriad  titles  invoked  on  the 

stammering  lips  that  are  human, 
Among  them  "Atsu-su-namir," 

and  it  meaneth  "His  Rising  is  seen." 

"To  realm  whence  no  echo  is  borne, 

to  region  no  pioneer  showeth ; 
To  the  Castle  of  Darkness  Substantial; 

to  Yesterday's  shadowy  shore 
Descend!"  quoth  the  Infinite  One, 

"for  the  calm  of  the  tempest  that  bloweth 
From  Allat  the  Queen  of  Irkalla, 

the  dame  of  the  seven-fold  door! 

"Command  her,  in  name  of  her  Father, 

to  give  from  the  Fount  of  Revival 
Unto  Istar  her  captive  a  draught 

for  the  raising  of  Tammuz  the  Slain. 
If  pity  she  will  not  bestow 

on  the  need  of  her  sister  and  rival, 
Then  warn  her  how  fragile  Death's  fetter 

the  gods  Love  and  Life  to  restrain!" 


THE  WEIRD  OF  LOVE  AND  DEATH.  26$ 

More  swift  than  the  flight  of  a  star 

was  the  radiant  herald  in  falling, 
Through  the  limitless  ether  conveyed 

on  the  thought  of  the  Uttermost  God. 
O'er  the  Sea  of  Oblivion  borne 

to  the  Island  of  Silence  appalling 
Where  hinges  of  Hell  broke  asunder 

at  touch  of  a  magical  rod. 

Yet  Allat,  the  Queen  of  the  Dead, 

at  the  luminous  shape  hurl'd  reviling: 
"Though  I  may  not  deny  nor  delay 

my  Father's  unwelcome  behest, 
Atsu-su-namir,  with  the  face 

that  is  evermore  hopeful  and  smiling, 
I  curse  thee,  who  bringest  His  will!" 

and  she  beat  her  implacable  breast. 

"Go,  Namtar,  and  knock  at  the  pillars 

that  hold  up  the  base  of  our  dwelling; 
Bid  the  gnomes  in  their  cavern  assemble 

and  sit  on  their  benches  of  gold; 
Let  Istar  the  water  receive 

that  in  Fount  of  Revival  is  welling, 
And  bring  back  the  goddess  before  us; 

her  boon  we  no  more  may  withhold." 

Though  grudgingly  made  the  release, 

through  the  seven-fold  gate  Lady  Istar 
In  her  strength  and  her  beauty  renewed, 

from  the  Castle  of  Darkness  hath  gone. 
No  warden  might  check  or  betray, 

no  padlock  nor  bar  might  resist  her; 
With  mantle  and  jewels  restored 

her  figure  resplendently  shone. 


266  THE  MONIST. 

She  bore  in  her  hand  a  bright  chalice 

for  wakening  Tammuz  the  Sleeper; 
For  Adonis,  the  First-fruits  of  Death, 

an  immortal  libation  she  poured; 
While  hymns  from  the  farthest  confines 

of  creation  grew  louder  and  deeper, 
As  flowers  and  fishes  and  beasts 

with  mankind  her  arising  adored: 

"In  Valley  of  Life  there  is  growing 

a  tree  amaranthine  and  shady; 
From  the  grail  of  the  crystal  abyss 

the  sap  of  its  verdure  is  drawn; 
In  heart  of  the  earth  it  is  rooted, 

its  leaves  form  the  nest  of  Our  Lady 
Whose  star  in  the  highway  of  Heaven 

enlight'neth  the  dusk  and  the  dawn! 

"Enshrined  in  a  mystery  sweet 

is  Adonis  the  Beautiful  lying 
On  the  lap  of  the  Mother  Divine 

who  lamented  him  cruelly  slain. 
There  bloometh  the  garden  of  love, 

and  the  flower  of  life  is  undying, 
Beyond  the  soft  veil  of  the  temple 

that  hideth  the  deities  twain! 

"O  Tammuz,  our  Lord  and  our  Shepherd! 

Miraculous  Bridegroom  of  Istar! 
Thou  hast  conquered  the  stronghold  of  Death 

and  thou  leadest  thy  people  like  sheep! 
Thou  wert  as  the  wheat  in  the  field 

that  a  wind  of  the  desert  doth  blister, 
Like  tree  of  acacia  with  root 

that  a  treacherous  river  doth  steep! 


THE  WEIRD  OF  LOVE  AND  DEATH.  267 

"Our  Lady,  whose  star  in  the  sky 

bringeth  hope  to  the  heart  heavy-laden, 
And  whose  justice  on  earth  is  a  lion, 

whose  mercy  a  lamb  at  the  breast, 
O  Queen  of  the  House  of  the  Shepherd, 

O  Mistress  of  Love  ever-maiden, 
May  infinite  joy  be  upon  thee, 

thy  grief  be  forever  at  rest!" 

EDWARD  GILCHRIST. 
SWATOW,  CHINA. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

THE  REV.  JAMES  BRADLEY  ON  THE  MOTION  OF  THE 

FIXED  STARS. 
(Reprinted  from  the  Philosophical  Transactions  of  1727.) 

[The  theory  of  the  relativity  of  time  and  space,  which  is  at  present  upper- 
most in  the  minds  of  physicists,  has  come  into  the  foreground  mainly  through 
the  differences  of  measuring  at  large  distances  the  time  it  takes  light  to 
reach  the  observer's  eye  which  is  further  complicated  by  the  motions  of  his 
own  standpoint.  This  happened  for  the  first  time  in  the  history  of  science  in 
the  year  1726  when  Mr.  Bradley  discovered  that  the  fixed  stars  possessed 
a  definite  and  peculiar  motion  of  their  own  which  was  due  to  the  motion  of 
the  earth  around  the  sun  and  depended  on  the  time  it  takes  the  light  to  reach 
the  earth. 

This  classical  exposition  of  his  experiments  was  published  in  the  form  of  a 
letter  sent  to  the  Phil.  Trans.  (Vol.  XXXIV,  p.  637)  and  has  naturally  become 
quite  inaccessible.  There  is  probably  only  one  complete  file  of  the  Trans- 
actions west  of  the  Alleghanies,  the  fortunate  possessor  of  which  is  the 
Chicago  Public  Library.  Considering  the  rarity  of  this  essay  we  deem  it 
proper  to  republish  it  and  render  it  accessible  to  our  readers.  We  do  not 
doubt  the  very  way  in  which  Mr.  Bradley  approaches  the  problem  will  throw 
much  light  on  the  principle  of  relativity.  In  fact  this  essay  will  prove  suffi- 
cient to  explain  its  far-reaching  significance,  the  need  of  its  invention  and 
the  limitations  of  its  use.  A  consideration  of  the  foundaton  of  this  principle 
and  the  history  of  its  origin  will  clear  it  of  the  mysticism  with  which  its  recent 
representations  have  surrounded  its  statements. — p.  c] 

A  Letter  from  the  Reverend  Mr.  James  Bradley,  Savilian  Professor 
of  Astronomy  at  Oxford,  and  F.  R.  S.,  to  Dr.  Edmond  Halley 
Astronom.  Reg.  &c.  giving  an  Account  of  a  new  discovered 
Motion  of  the  Fix'd  Stars. 
SIR, 

You  having  been  pleased  to  express  your  Satisfaction  with  what 
I  had  an  Opportunity  some  time  ago,  of  telling  you  in  Conversation, 
concerning  some  Observations,  that  were  making  by  our  late  worthy 
and  ingenious  Friend,  the  honorable  Samuel  Molyneux  Esquire,  and 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  269 

which  have  since  been  continued  and  repeated  by  myself,  in  order 
to  determine  the  Parallax  of  the  fixt  Stars ;  I  shall  now  beg  leave 
to  lay  before  you  a  more  particular  Account  of  them. 

Before  I  proceed  to  give  you  the  History  of  the  Observations 
themselves,  it  may  be  proper  to  let  you  know,  that  they  were  at 
first  begun  in  hopes  of  verifying  and  confirming  those,  that  Dr. 
Hook  formerly  communicated  to  the  publick,  which  seemed  to  be 
attended  with  Circumstances  that  promised  greater  Exactness  in 
them,  than  could  be  expected  in  any  other,  that  had  been  made  and 
published  on  the  same  Account.  And  as  his  Attempt  was  what 
principally  gave  Rise  to  this,  so  his  Method  in  making  the  Observa- 
tions was  in  some  Measure  that  which  Mr.  Molyneux  followed :  For 
he  made  Choice  of  the  same  Star,  and  his  Instrument  was  con- 
structed upon  almost  the  same  Principles.  But  if  it  had  not  greatly 
exceeded  the  Doctor's  in  Exactness,  we  might  yet  have  remained 
in  great  Uncertainty  as  to  the  Parallax  of  the  fixt  Stars ;  as  you 
will  perceive  upon  the  Comparison  of  the  two  Experiments. 

This  indeed  was  chiefly  owing  to  our  curious  Member,  Mr. 
George  Graham,  to  whom  the  Lovers  of  Astronomy  are  also  not  a  little 
indebted  for  several  other  exact  and  well-contrived  Instruments. 
The  Necessity  of  such  will  scarce  be  disputed  by  those  that  have  had 
any  Experience  in  making  Astronomical  Observations ;  and  the  In- 
consistency, which  is  to  be  met  with  among  different  Authors  in 
their  Attempts  to  determine  small  Angles,  particularly  the  annual 
Parallax  of  the  fixt  Stars,  may  be  a  sufficient  Proof  of  it  to  others. 
Their  Disagreement  indeed  in  this  article  is  not  now  so  much  to  be 
wondered  at,  since  I  doubt  not,  but  it  will  appear  very  probable, 
that  the  Instruments  commonly  made  use  of  by  them,  were  liable 
to  greater  Errors  than  many  times  that  Parallax  will  amount  to. 

The  Success  then  of  this  Experiment  evidently  depending  very 
much  on  the  Accurateness  of  the  Instrument  that  was  principally 
to  be  taken  Care  of:  In  what  Manner  this  was  done,  is  not  my 
present  Purpose  to  tell  you ;  but  if  from  the  Result  of  the  Observa- 
tions which  I  now  send  you,  it  shall  be  judged  necessary  to  com- 
municate to  the  Curious  the  Manner  of  making  them,  I  may  here- 
after perhaps  give  them  a  particular  Description,  not  only  of  Mr. 
Molyneux 's  Instrument  but  also  of  my  own,  which  hath  since  been 
erected  for  the  same  Purpose  and  upon  the  like  Principles,  though 
it  is  somewhat  different  in  its  Construction,  for  a  Reason  you  will 
meet  with  presently. 

Mr.  Molyneux's  Apparatus  was  compleated  and  fitted  for  ob- 


2/O  THE  MONIST. 

serving  about  the  End  of  November  1725,  and  on  the  third  Day 
of  December  following,  the  bright  Star  at  the  Head  of  Draco 
(marked  v  by  Bayer)  was  for  the  first  Time  observed,  as  it  passed 
near  the  Zenith,  and  its  Situation  carefully  taken  with  the  Instru- 
ment. The  like  Observations  were  made  on  the  5th,  llth  and  12th 
Days  of  the  same  Month,  and  there  appearing  no  material  Difference 
in  the  Place  of  the  Star,  a  farther  Repetition  of  them  at  this  Season 
seemed  needless,  it  being  a  Part  of  the  Year,  wherein  no  sensible 
Alteration  of  Parallax  in  this  Star  could  be  expected.  It  was  chiefly 
therefore  Curiosity  that  tempted  me  (being  then  at  Kew,  where  the 
Instrument  was  fixed)  to  prepare  for  observing  the  Star  on  Decem- 
ber 17th,  when  having  adjusted  the  Instrument  as  usual,  I  per- 
ceived that  it  passed  a  little  more  Southerly  this  Day  than  when  it 
was  observed  before.  Not  suspecting  any  other  Cause  of  this  Ap- 
pearance, we  first  concluded,  that  it  was  owing  to  the  Uncertainty 
of  the  Observations,  and  that  either  this  or  the  foregoing  were  not 
so  exact  as  we  had  before  supposed ;  for  which  Reason  we  purposed 
to  repeat  the  Observation  again,  in  order  to  determine  from  whence 
this  Difference  proceeded;  and  upon  doing  it  on  December  20th,  I 
found  that  the  Star  passed  still  more  Southerly  than  in  the  former 
Observations.  This  sensible  Alteration  the  more  surprized  us,  in 
that  it  was  the  contrary  way  from  what  it  would  have  been,  had  it 
proceeded  from  an  annual  Parallax  of  the  Star:  But  being  now 
pretty  well  satisfied,  that  it  could  not  be  entirely  owing  to  the  want 
of  Exactness  in  the  Observations ;  and  having  no  Notion  of  anything 
else,  that  could  cause  such  an  apparent  Motion  as  this  in  the  Star; 
we  began  to  think  that  some  Change  in  the  Materials,  &c.  of  the 
Instrument  itself,  might  have  occasioned  it.  Under  these  Apprehen- 
sions we  remained  some  time,  but  being  at  length  fully  convinced, 
by  several  Trials,  of  the  great  Exactness  of  the  Instrument,  and 
finding  by  the  gradual  Increase  of  the  Star's  Distance  from  the  Pole, 
that  there  must  be  some  regular  Cause  that  produced  it;  we  took 
care  to  examine  nicely,  at  the  Time  of  each  Observation,  how  much 
it  was:  and  about  the  Beginning  of  March  1725,  the  Star  was  found 
to  be  20"  more  Southerly  than  at  the  Time  of  the  first  Observation. 
It  now  indeed  seemed  to  have  arrived  at  its  utmost  Limit  Southward, 
because  in  several  Trials  made  about  this  Time,  no  sensible  Differ- 
ence was  observed  in  its  Situation.  By  the  Middle  of  April,  it 
appeared  to  be  returning  back  again  towards  the  North;  and  about 
the  beginning  of  June,  it  passed  at  the  same  Distance  from  the 
Zenith  as  it  had  done  in  December  when  it  was  first  observed. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

From  the  quick  Alteration  of  this  Star's  Declination  about  this 
Time  (it  increasing  a  Second  in  three  Days)  it  was  concluded,  that 
it  would  now  proceed  Northward,  as  it  before  had  done  Southward 
of  its  present  Situation;  and  it  happened  as  was  conjectured:  for 
the  Star  continued  to  move  Northward  till  September  following, 
when  it  again  became  stationary,  being  then  near  20"  more  Northerly 
than  in  June,  and  no  less  than  39"  more  Northerly  than  it  was  in 
March.  From  September  the  Star  returned  towards  the  South,  till 
it  arrived  in  December  to  the  same  Situation  it  was  in  at  that  time 
twelve  Months,  allowing  for  the  Difference  of  Declination  on  account 
of  the  Precession  of  the  Equinox. 

This  was  a  sufficient  Proof,  that  the  Instrument  had  not  been 
the  Cause  of  this  apparent  Motion  of  the  Star,  and  to  find  one 
adequate  to  such  an  Effect  seemed  a  Difficulty.  A  Nutation  of  the 
Earth's  Axis  was  one  of  the  first  things  that  offered  itself  upon  this 
Occasion,  but  it  was  soon  found  to  be  insufficient;  for  though  it 
might  have  accounted  for  the  change  of  Declination  in  v  Draconis 
yet  it  would  not  at  the  same  time  agree  with  the  Phaenomena  in 
other  Stars ;  particularly  in  a  small  one  almost  opposite  in  right 
Ascension  to  v  Draconis,  at  about  the  same  Distance  from  the  North 
Pole  of  the  Equator:  For,  though  this  Star  seemed  to  move  the 
same  way,  as  a  Nutation  of  the  Earth's  Axis  would  have  made  it, 
yet  it  changing  its  Declination  but  about  half  as  much  as  v  Draconis 
in  the  same  time  (as  appeared  upon  comparing  the  Observations  of 
both  made  upon  the  same  Days,  at  different  Seasons  of  the  Year) 
this  plainly  proved,  that  the  apparent  Motion  of  the  Stars  was  not 
occasioned  by  a  real  Nutation,  since  if  that  had  been  the  Cause,  the 
Alteration  in  both  Stars  would  have  been  near  equal. 

The  great  Regularity  of  the  Observations  left  no  room  to  doubt, 
but  that  there  was  some  regular  Cause  that  produced  this  unex- 
pected Motion,  which  did  not  depend  on  the  Uncertainty  or  Variety 
of  the  Seasons  of  the  Year.  Upon  comparing  the  Observations 
with  each  other,  it  was  discovered  that  in  both  the  fore-mentioned 
Stars,  the  apparent  Difference  of  Declination  from  the  Maxima,  was 
always  nearly  proportional  to  the  versed  Sine  of  the  Sun's  Distance 
from  the  Equinoctial  Points.  This  was  an  Inducement  to  think, 
that  the  Cause,  whatever  it  was,  had  some  Relation  to  the  Sun's 
Situation  with  respect  to  those  Points.  But  not  being  able  to  frame  any 
Hypothesis  at  that  Time  sufficient  to  solve  all  the  Phaenomena,  and 
being  very  desirous  to  search  a  little  farther  into  this  Matter ;  I  began 
to  think  of  erecting  an  Instrument  for  myself  at  Wansted,  that 


272  THE  MONIST. 

having  it  always  at  Hand,  I  might  with  the  more  Ease  and  Certainty, 
enquire  into  the  Laws  of  this  new  Motion.  The  Consideration  like- 
wise of  being  able  by  another  Instrument,  to  confirm  the  Truth  of 
the  Observations  hitherto  made  with  Mr.  Molyneux's,  was  no  small 
Inducement  to  me ;  but  the  Chief  of  all  was,  the  Opportunity  I  should 
thereby  have  of  trying,  in  what  Manner  other  Stars  were  affected 
by  the  same  Cause,  whatever  it  was.  For  Mr.  Molyneux's  Instru- 
ment being  originally  designed  for  observing  v  Draconis  (in  order 
as  I  said  before,  to  try  whether  it  had  any  sensible  Parallax)  was 
so  contrived,  as  to  be  capable  of  but  little  Alteration  in  its  Direc- 
tion, not  above  seven  or  eight  Minutes  of  a  Degree;  and  there 
being  few  stars  within  half  that  Distance  from  the  Zenith  of  Kew, 
bright  enough  to  be  well  observed,  he  could  not,  with  his  Instru- 
ment, thoroughly  examine  how  this  Cause  affected  Stars  differently 
situated  with  respect  to  the  equinoctial  and  solstitial  Points  of  the 
Ecliptick. 

These  Considerations  determined  me;  and  by  the  Contrivance 
and  Direction  of  the  same  ingenious  Person,  Mr.  Graham,  my  In- 
strument was  fixed  up  August  19,  1727.  As  I  had  no  convenient 
Place  where  I  could  made  use  of  so  long  a  Telescope  as  Mr.  Moly- 
neux's, I  contented  myself  with  one  of  but  little  more  than  half  the 
Length  of  his  (viz.  of  about  \2\  Feet,  his  being  24 J)  judging  from 
the  Experience  which  I  had  already  had,  that  this  Radius  would  be 
long  enough  to  adjust  the  Instrument  to  a  sufficient  Degree  of 
Exactness,  and  I  have  no  reason  since  to  change  my  Opinion:  for 
from  all  the  Trials  I  have  yet  made,  I  am  very  well  satisfied,  that 
when  it  is  carefully  rectified,  its  Situation  may  be  securely  depended 
upon  to  half  a  Second.  As  the  Place  where  my  Instrument  was  to 
be  hung,  in  some  Measure  determined  its  Radius,  so  did  it  also  the 
Length  of  the  Arch,  or  Limb,  on  which  the  Divisions  were  made  to 
adjust  it:  For  the  Arch  could  not  conveniently  be  extended  farther, 
than  to  reach  to  about  6J°  on  each  Side  my  Zenith.  This  indeed 
was  sufficient,  since  it  gave  me  an  Opportunity  of  making  Choice 
of  several  Stars,  very  different  both  in  Magnitude  and  Situation ; 
there  being  more  than  two  hundred  inserted  in  the  British  Catalogue, 
that  may  be  observed  with  it.  I  needed  not  to  have  extended  the 
Limb  so  far,  but  that  I  was  willing  to  take  in  Capella,  the  only  star 
of  the  first  Magnitude  that  comes  so  near  my  Zenith. 

My  instrument  being  fixed,  I  immediately  began  to  observe 
such  Stars  as  I  judged  most  proper  to  give  me  light  into  the  Cause 
of  the  Motion  already  mentioned.  There  was  Variety  enough  of 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  2/3 

small  ones;  and  not  less  than  twelve,  that  I  could  observe  through 
all  the  Seasons  of  the  Year;  they  being  bright  enough  to  be  seen 
in  the  Day-time,  when  nearest  the  Sun.  I  had  not  been  long  ob- 
serving, before  I  perceived,  that  the  Notion  we  had  before  enter- 
tained of  the  Stars  being  farthest  North  and  South,  when  the  Sun 
was  about  the  Equinoxes,  was  only  true  of  those  that  were  near  the 
solstitial  Colure:  And  after  I  had  continued  my  Observations  a  few 
Months,  I  discovered,  what  I  then  apprehended  to  be  a  general 
Law,  observed  by  all  the  Stars,  viz.  That  each  of  them  became  sta- 
tionary, or  was  farthest  North  or  South,  when  they  passed  over  my 
Zenith  at  six  of  the  Clock,  either  in  the  Morning  or  Evening.  I 
perceived  likewise,  that  whatever  Situation  the  Stars  were  in  with 
respect  to  the  cardinal  Points  of  the  Ecliptick,  the  apparent  motion 
of  every  one  tended  the  same  Way,  when  they  passed  my  instrument 
about  the  same  Hour  of  the  Day  or  Night;  for  they  all  moved 
Southward,  while  they  passed  in  the  Day,  and  Northward  in  the 
Night ;  so  that  each  was  farthest  North,  when  it  came  about  Six 
of  the  Clock  in  the  Evening,  and  farther  South,  when  it  came  about 
Six  in  the  Morning. 

Though  I  have  since  discovered,  that  the  Maxima  in  most  of 
these  Stars  do  not  happen  exactly  when  they  come  to  my  Instrument 
at  those  Hours,  yet  not  being  able  at  that  time  to  prove  the  con- 
trary, and  supposing  that  they  did,  I  endeavoured  to  find  out  what 
Proportion  the  greatest  Alterations  of  Declination  in  different  Stars 
bore  to  each  other ;  it  being  very  evident,  that  they  did  not  all  change 
their  Declination  equally.  I  have  before  taken  notice,  that  it  ap- 
peared from  Mr.  Molyneux's  Observations,  that  v  Draconis  altered 
its  Declination  about  twice  as  much  as  the  fore-mentioned  small 
Star  almost  opposite  to  it ;  but  examining  the  matter  more  particu- 
larly, I  found  that  the  greatest  Alteration  of  Declination  in  these 
Stars,  was  at  the  Sine  of  the  Latitude  of  each  respectively.  This 
made  me  suspect  that  there  might  be  the  like  Proportion  between 
the  Maxima  of  other  Stars ;  but  finding,  that  the  observations  of 
some  of  them  would  not  perfectly  correspond  with  such  an  Hypoth- 
esis, and  not  knowing,  whether  the  small  Difference  I  met  with, 
might  not  be  owing  to  the  Uncertainty  and  Error  of  the  Observa- 
tions, I  deferred  the  farther  examination  into  the  Truth  of  this 
Hypothesis,  till  I  should  be  furnished  with  a  Series  of  Observations 
made  in  all  Parts  of  the  Year ;  which  might  enable  me,  not  only  to 
determine  what  Errors  the  Observations  are  liable  to,  or  how  far 


274 


THE  MONIST. 


they  may  safely  be  depended  upon;  but  also  to  judge,  whether  there 
had  been  any  sensible  Change  in  the  Parts  of  the  Instrument  itself. 

Upon  these  Considerations,  I  laid  aside  all  Thoughts  at  that 
Time  about  the  Cause  of  the  fore-mentioned  Phaenomena,  hoping 
that  I  should  the  easier  discover  it,  when  I  was  better  provided  with 
proper  Means  to  determine  more  precisely  what  they  were. 

When  the  Year  was  compleated,  I  began  to  examine  and  com- 
pare my  Observations,  and  having  pretty  well  satisfied  myself  as  to 
the  general  Laws  of  the  Phaenomena,  I  then  endeavoured  to  find 
out  the  Cause,  of  them.  I  was  already  convinced,  that  the  apparent 
Motion  of  the  Stars,  was  not  owing  to  a  Nutation  of  the  Earth's 
Axis.  The  next  Thing  that  offered  itself,  was  an  Alteration  in  the 


Direction  of  the  Plumb-line,  with  which  the  Instrument  was  con- 
stantly rectified ;  but  this  upon  Trial  proved  insufficient.  Then  I 
considered  what  Refraction  might  do,  but  here  also  nothing  satis- 
factory occurred.  At  last  I  conjectured,  that  all  the  Phaenomena 
hitherto  mentioned,  proceeded  from  the  progressive  Motion  of  Light 
and  the  Earth's  annual  Motion  in  its  Orbit.  For  I  perceived,  that, 
if  Light  was  propagated  in  Time,  the  apparent  Place  of  a  fixt  Ob- 
ject would  not  be  the  same  when  the  Eye  is  at  Rest,  as  when  it  is 
moving  in  any  other  Direction,  than  that  of  the  Line  passing  through 
the  Eye  and  Object;  and  that,  when  the  Eye  is  moving  in  different 
Directions,  the  apparent  Place  of  the  Object  would  be  different. 

I  considered  this  Matter  in  the  following  Manner.  I  imagined 
CA  to  be  a  Ray  of  Light,  falling  perpendicularly  upon  the  Line  BD ; 
then  if  the  Eye  is  at  rest  at  A,  the  Object  must  appear  in  the  Direc- 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  275 

tion  AC,  whether  Light  be  propagated  in  Time  or  in  an  Instant. 
But  if  the  Eye  is  moving  from  B  towards  A,  and  Light  is  propa- 
gated in  Time,  with  a  Velocity  that  is  to  the  Velocity  of  the  Eye, 
as  CA  to  BA;  then  Light  moving  from  C  to  A,  whilst  the  Eye 
moves  from  B  to  A,  that  Particle  of  it,  by  which  the  Object  will  be 
discerned,  when  the  Eye  in  its  Motion  comes  to  A,  is  at  C  when 
the  Eye  is  at  B.  Joining  the  Points  B,  C,  I  supposed  the  Line  CB, 
to  be  a  Tube  (inclined  to  the  Line  BD  in  the  Angle  DBC)  of  such 
a  Diameter,  as  to  admit  of  but  one  Particle  of  Light;  then  it  was 
easy  to  conceive,  that  the  Particle  of  Light  at  C  (by  which  the  ob- 
ject must  be  seen  when  the  Eye,  as  it  moves  along,  arrives  at  A) 
would  pass  through  the  Tube  BC,  if  it  is  inclined  to  BD  in  the  Angle 
DBC,  and  accompanies  the  Eye  in  its  Motion  from  B  to  A ;  and  that 
it  could  not  come  to  the  Eye,  placed  behind  such  a  Tube,  if  it  had 
any  other  Inclination  to  the  Line  BD.  If  instead  of  supposing  CB 
so  small  a  Tube,  we  imagine  it  to  be  the  Axis  of  a  larger ;  then  for 
the  same  Reason,  the  Particle  of  Light  at  C,  could  not  pass  through 
that  Axis,  unless  it  is  inclined  to  BD,  in  the  Angle  CBD.  In  like 
manner,  if  the  Eye  moved  the  contrary  way,  from  D  towards  A, 
with  the  same  Velocity ;  then  the  Tube  must  be  inclined  in  the  Angle 
BDC.  Although  therefore  the  true  or  real  Place  of  an  Object  is 
perpendicular  to  the  Line  in  which  the  Eye  is  moving,  yet  the  vis- 
ible Place  will  not  be  so,  since  that,  no  doubt,  must  be  in  the  Direc- 
tion of  the  Tube ;  but  the  Difference  between  the  true  and  apparent 
Place  will  be  (cateris  paribus)  greater  or  less,  according  to  the 
different  Proportion  between  the  Velocity  of  Light  and  that  of  the 
Eye.  So  that  if  we  could  suppose  that  Light  was  propagated  in 
an  instant,  then  there  would  be  no  Difference  between  the  real  and 
visible  Place  of  an  Object,  although  the  Eye  were  in  Motion,  for 
in  that  case,  AC  being  infinite  with  Respect  to  AB,  the  Angle  ACB 
(the  Difference  between  the  true  and  visible  Place)  vanishes.  But 
if  Light  be  propagated  in  Time  (which  I  presume  will  readily  be 
allowed  by  most  of  the  Philosophers  of  this  Age)  then  it  is  evident 
from  the  foregoing  Considerations,  that  there  will  be  always  a 
Difference  between  the  real  and  visible  Place  of  an  Object,  unless 
the  Eye*  is  moving  either  directly  towards  or  from  the  Object.  And 
in  all  Cases,  the  Sine  of  the  Difference  between  the  real  and  visible 
Place  of  the  Object,  will  be  to  the  Sine  of  the  visible  Inclination 
of  the  Object  to  the  Line  in  which  the  Eye  is  moving,  as  the  Veloc- 
ity of  the  Eye  to  the  Velocity  of  Light. 

If  Light  moved  but  1000  times  faster  than  the  Eye,  and  an  Ob- 


2/6  THE  MONIST. 

ject  (supposed  to  be  at  an  infinite  Distance)  was  really  placed  perpen- 
dicularly over  the  Plain  in  which  the  Eye  is  moving,  it  follows  from 
what  hath  been  already  said,  that  the  apparent  Place  of  such  an 
Object  will  be  always  inclined  to  that  Plain,  in  an  Angle  of  89°  56'-J ; 
so  that  it  will  constantly  appear  3'^  from  its  true  Place,  and  seem 
so  much  less  inclined  to  the  Plain,  that  way  towards  which  the  Eye 
tends.  That  is,  if  AC  is  to  AB  (or  AD)  as  1000  to  one,  the  Angle 
ABC  will  be  89°  56'i,  and  ACB  =  3'i  and  BCD  ^  2ACB  =  7'. 
So  that  according  to  this  Supposition,  the  visible  or  apparent  Place 
of  the  Object  will  be  altered  7',  if  the  Direction  of  the  Eye's  Motion 
is  at  one  time  contrary  to  what  it  is  at  another. 

If  the  Earth  revolve  round  the  Sun  annually,  and  the  Velocity 
of  Light  were  to  the  Velocity  of  the  Earth's  Motion  in  its  Orbit 
(which  I  will  at  present  suppose  to  be  a  Circle)  as  1000  to  one ;  then 
tis  easy  to  conceive,  that  a  Star  really  placed  in  the  very  Pole  of  the 
Ecliptick,  would,  to  an  Eye  carried  along  with  the  Earth,  seem  to 
change  its  Place  continually,  and  (neglecting  the  small  Difference 
on  the  Account  of  the  Earth's  diurnal  Revolution  on  its  Axis)  would 
seem  to  describe  a  Circle  round  that  Pole,  every  Way  distant  there- 
from 3'|.  So  that  its  Longitude  would  be  varied  through  all  the 
Points  of  the  Ecliptick  every  Year ;  but  its  Latitude  would  always 
remain  the  same.  Its  right  Ascension  would  also  change,  and  its 
Declination,  according  to  the  different  Situation  of  the  Sun  in  respect 
to  the  equinoctial  Points ;  and  its  apparent  Distance  from  the  North 
Pole  of  the  Equator  would  be  7'  less  at  the  Autumnal,  than  at  the 
vernal  Equinox. 

The  greatest  Alteration  of  the  Place  of  a  Star  in  the  Pole  of 
the  Ecliptick  (or  which  in  Effect  amounts  to  the  same,  the  Propor- 
tion between  the  Velocity  of  Light  and  the  Earth's  Motion  in  its 
Orbit)  being  known ;  it  will  not  be  difficult  to  find  what  would  be 
the  Difference  upon  this  Account,  the  Difference  between  the  true 
and  apparent  Place  of  any  other  Star  at  any  time ;  and  on  the  con- 
trary, the  Difference  between  the  true  and  apparent  Place  being 
given ;  the  Proportion  between  the  Velocity  of  Light  and  the  Earth's 
Motion  in  its  Orbit  may  be  found. 

As  I  only  observed  the  apparent  Difference  of  Declination  of 
the  Stars,  I  shall  not  now  take  any  farther  Notice  in  what  manner 
such  a  Cause  as  I  have  here  supposed  would  occasion  an  Alteration 
in  their  apparent  Places  in  other  Respects ;  but,  supposing  the  Earth 
to  move  equally  in  a  Circle,  it  may  be  gathered  from  what  hath  been 
already  said,  that  a  Star  which  is  neither  in  the  Pole  nor  Plain  of 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  277 

the  Ecliptick,  will  seem  to  describe  about  its  true  Place  a  Figure, 
insensibly  different  from  an  Ellipse,  whose  Transverse  Axis  is  at 
Right-angle  to  the  Circle  of  Longitude  passing  through  the  Star's 
true  Place,  and  equal  to  the  Diameter  of  the  little  Circle  described 
by  a  Star  (as  was  before  supposed)  in  the  Pole  of  the  Ecliptick ; 
and  whose  Conjugate  Axis  is  to  its  Transverse  Axis,  as  the  Sine 
of  the  Star's  latitude  to  the  Radius.  And  allowing  that  a  Star  by  its 
apparent  Motion  does  exactly  describe  such  an  Ellipse,  it  will  be 
found,  that  if  A  be  the  Angle  of  Position  (or  the  Angle  at  the  Star 
made  by  two  great  Circles  drawn  from  it,  thro'  the  Poles  of  the 
Ecliptick  and  Equator)  and  B  be  another  Angle,  whose  Tangent  is 
to  the  Tangent  of  A  as  Radius  to  the  Sine  of  the  Latitude  of  the 
Star;  then  B  will  be  equal  to  the  Difference  of  Longitude  between 
the  Sun  and  the  Star,  when  the  true  and  apparent  Declination  of 
the  Star  are  the  same.  And  if  the  Sun's  Longitude  in  the  Ecliptick 
be  reckoned  from  that  Point,  wherein  it  is  when  this  happens ;  then 
the  Difference  between  the  true  and  apparent  Declination  of  the 
Star  (on  account  of  the  Cause  I  am  now  considering)  will  be  always, 
as  the  Sine  of  the  Sun's  Longitude  from  thence.  It  will  likewise 
be  found,  that  the  greatest  Difference  of  Declination  that  can  be 
between  the  true  and  apparent  Place  of  the  Star,  will  be  to  the  Semi- 
Transverse  Axis  of  the  Ellipse  (or  to  the  Semi-diameter  of  the 
little  Circle  described  by  a  Star  in  the  Pole  of  the  Ecliptick)  as  the 
Sine  of  A  to  the  Sine  of  B. 

If  the  Star  hath  North  Latitude,  the  Time,  when  its  true  and 
apparent  Declination  are  the  same,  is  before  the  Sun  comes  in  Con- 
junction with  or  Opposition  to  it,  if  its  Longitude  be  in  the  first  or 
last  Quadrant  (viz.  in  the  ascending  Semi-circle)  of  the  Ecliptick; 
and  after  them,  if  in  the  descending  Semi-circle ;  and  it  will  appear 
nearest  to  the  North  Pole  of  the  Equator,  at  the  Time  of  that 
Maximum  (or  when  the  greatest  Difference  between  the  true  and 
apparent  Declination  happens)  which  precedes  the  Sun's  Conjunc- 
tion with  the  Star. 

These  Particulars  being  sufficient  for  my  present  Purpose,  I 
shall  not  detain  you  with  the  Recital  of  any  more,  or  with  any  farther 
Explication  of  these.  It  may  be  time  enough  to  enlarge  more  upon 
this  Head,  when  I  give  a  Description  of  the  Instruments  &c.  if  that 
be  judged  necessary  to  be  done;  and  when  I  shall  find,  what  I  now 
advance,  to  be  allowed  of  (as  I  flatter  myself  it  will)  as  something 
more  than  a  bare  Hypothesis.  I  have  purposely  omitted  some  mat- 
ters of  no  great  Moment,  and  considerd  the  Earth  as  moving  in  a 


2/8  THE  MONIST. 

Circle,  and  not  an  Ellipse,  to  avoid  too  perplexed  a  Calculus,  which 
after  all  the  Trouble  of  it  would  not  sensibly  differ  from  that  which 
I  make  use  of,  especially  in  those  Consequences  which  I  shall  at 
present  draw  from  the  foregoing  Hypothesis. 

This  being  premised,  I  shall  not  proceed  to  determine  from  the 
observations,  what  the  real  Proportion  is  between  the  Velocity  of 
Light  and  the  Velocity  of  the  Earth's  annual  Motion  in  its  Orbit; 
upon  Supposition  that  the  Phaenomena  before  mentioned  do  depend 
upon  the  Causes  I  have  here  assigned.  But  I  must  first  let  you  know, 
that  in  all  the  Observations  hereafter  mentioned,  I  have  made  an 
Allowance  for  the  Change  of  the  Star's  Declination  on  Account  of 
the  Precession  of  the  Equinox,  upon  Supposition  that  the  Alteration 
from  this  Cause  is  proportional  to  the  Time,  and  regular  through  all 
the  Parts  of  the  Year.  I  have  deduced  the  real  annual  Alteration 
of  Declination  of  each  Star  from  the  Observations  themselves ;  and 
I  the  rather  choose  to  depend  upon  them  in  this  Article,  because  all 
which  I  have  yet  made,  concur  to  prove,  that  the  Stars  near  the 
Equinoctial  Colure,  change  their  Declination  at  this  time  1"£  or  2" 
in  a  Year  more  than  they  would  do  if  the  Precession  was  only  50", 
as  is  now  generally  supposed.  I  have  likewise  met  with  some  small 
Varieties  in  the  Declination  of  other  Stars  in  different  Years,  which 
do  not  seem  to  proceed  from  the  same  Cause,  particularly  in  those 
that  are  near  the  solstitial  Colure,  which  on  the  contrary  have  altered 
their  Declination  less  than  they  ought,  if  the  Precession  was  50". 
But  whether  these  small  Alterations  proceed  from  a  regular  Cause, 
or  are  occasioned  by  any  Change  in  the  Materials  &c.  of  my  Instru- 
ment, I  am  not  yet  able  fully  to  determine.  However,  I  thought  it 
might  not  be  amiss  just  to  mention  to  you  how  I  have  endeavoured 
to  allow  for  them,  though  the  Result  would  have  been  nearly  the 
same,  if  I  had  not  considered  them  at  all.  What  that  is,  I  will  shew, 
first  from  the  Observations  of  v  Draconis,  which  was  found  to  be 
39"  more  Southerly  in  the  Beginning  of  March,  than  in  September. 

From  what  hath  been  premised,  it  will  appear  that  the  greatest 
Alteration  of  the  apparent  Declination  of  v  Draconis,  on  account  of 
the  successive  Propagation  of  Light,  would  be  to  the  Diameter  of 
the  little  Circle  which  a  Star  (as  was  before  remarked)  would  seem 
to  describe  about  the  Pole  of  the  Ecliptick  as  39"  to  40",  4.  The 
half  of  this  is  the  Angle  ACB  (as  represented  in  the  Fig.)  This 
therefore  being  20",  2,  AC  will  be  to  AB,  that  is,  the  Velocity  of 
Light  to  the  Velocity  of  the  Eye  (which  in  this  Case  may  be  sup- 
posed the  same  as  the  Velocity  of  the  Earth's  annual  Motion  in  its 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  279 

Orbit)  as  10210  to  One,  from  whence  it  would  follow,  that  Light 
moves,  or  is  propagated  as  far  as  from  the  Sun  to  the  Earth  in  8'  and 
12". 

It  is  well  known,  that  Mr.  Romer,  who  first  attempted  to 
account  for  an  apparent  Inequality  in  the  Times  of  the  Eclipses  of 
Jupiter's  Satellites,  by  the  Hypothesis  of  the  progressive  Motion 
of  Light,  supposed  that  it  spent  about  11  Minutes  of  Time  in  its 
Passage  from  the  Sun  to  us :  but  it  hath  since  been  concluded  by 
others  from  the  like  Eclipses,  that  it  is  propagated  as  far  in  about 
7  Minutes.  The  Velocity  of  Light  therefore  deduced  from  the  fore- 
going Hypothesis,  is  as  it  were  a  Mean  betwixt  what  had  at  different 
times  been  determined  from  the  Eclipses  of  Jupiter's  Satellites. 

These  different  Methods  of  finding  the  Velocity  of  Lig*ht 
thus  agreeing  in  the  Result,  we  may  reasonably  conclude,  not  only 
that  these  Phaenomena  are  owing  to  the  Causes  to  which  they  have 
been  ascribed;  but  also,  that  Light  is  propagated  (in  the  same 
Medium)  with  the  same  Velocity  after  it  hath  been  reflected  as 
before ;  for  this  will  be  the  Consequence,  if  we  allow  that  the  Light 
of  the  Sun  is  propagated  with  the  same  Velocity,  before  it  is  re- 
flected, as  the  Light  of  the  fixt  Stars.  And  I  imagine  this  will 
scarce  be  questioned,  if  it  can  be  made  appear  that  the  Velocity 
of  the  Light  of  all  the  fixt  Stars  is  equal,  and  that  their  Light  moves 
or  is  propagated  through  equal  Spaces  in  equal  Times,  at  all  Dis- 
tances from  them:  both  which  points  (as  I  apprehend)  are  suffi- 
ciently proved  from  the  apparent  alteration  of  the  Declination  of 
Stars  of  different  Lustre ;  for  that  is  not  sensibly  different  in  such 
Stars  as  seem  near  together,  though  they  appear  of  very  different 
Magnitudes.  And  whatever  their  Situations  are  (if  I  proceed  ac- 
cording to  the  foregoing  Hypothesis)  I  find  the  same  Velocity  of 
Light  from  my  Observations  of  small  Stars  of  the  fifth  or  sixth,  as 
from  those  of  the  second  and  third  Magnitude,  which  in  all  Proba- 
bility are  placed  at  very  different  Distances  from  us.  The  small 
Star,  for  Example,  before  spoken  of,  that  is  almost  opposite  to  v 
Draconis  (being  the  35th  Camelopard.  Hevelii  in  Mr.  Flamsteed's 
Catalogue)  was  19"  more  Northerly  about  the  Beginning  of  March 
than  in  September.  Whence  I  conclude,  according  to  my  Hypothesis, 
that  the  Diameter  of  the  little  Circle  described  by  a  Star  in  the 
Pole  of  the  Ecliptick  would  be  40",  2. 

The  last  Star  of  the  great  Bear's  tail  of  the  2d  Magnitude 
(marked  >/  by  Bayer)  was  36"  more  Southerly  about  the  Middle  of 
January  than  in  July.  Hence  the  Maximum,  or  greatest  Altera- 


28O  THE  MONIST. 

tion  of  Declination  of  a  Star  in  the  Pole  of  the  Ecliptick  would 
be  40",  4,  exactly  the  same  as  was  before  found  from  the  Observa- 
tions of  v  Draconis. 

The  Star  of  the  5th  magnitude  in  the  Head  of  Perseus  marked 
T  by  Bayer,  was  25"  more  Northerly  about  the  End  of  December 
than  on  the  29th  of  July  following.  Hence  the  Maximum  would 
be  41".  This  Star  is  not  bright  enough  to  be  seen  as  it  passes  over 
my  Zenith  about  the  End  of  June,  when  it  should  be  according  to 
the  Hypothesis  farthest  South.  But  because  I  can  more  certainly 
depend  upon  the  greatest  Alteration  of  Declination  of  those  Stars, 
which  I  have  frequently  observed  about  the  Times  when  they  be- 
come stationary,  with  respect  to  the  Motion  I  am  now  considering; 
I  will  set  down  a  few  more  Instances  of  such,  from  which  you  may 
be  able  to  judge  how  near  it  may  be  possible  from  these  Observa- 
tions, to  determine  with  what  Velocity  Light  is  propagated. 

a  Persei  Bayero  was  23"  more  Northerly  at  the  beginning  of 
January  than  in  July.  Hence  the  Maximum  would  be  40",  2.  a 
Cassiopece  was  34"  more  Northerly  about  the  End  of  December  than 
in  June.  Hence  the  Maximum  would  be  40",  8.  ft  Draconis  was  39" 
more  Northerly  in  the  beginning  of  September  than  in  March', 
hence  the  Maximum  would  be  40",  2.  Capella  was  about  16"  more 
Southerly  in  August  than  in  Feb. ;  hence  the  Maximum  would  be 
about  40".  But  this  Star  being  farther  from  my  Zenith  than  those 
I  have  before  made  use  of,  I  cannot  so  well  depend  upon  my  Ob- 
servations of  it,  as  of  the  others ;  because  I  meet  with  some  small 
Alterations  of  its  Declination  that  do  not  seem  to  proceed  from  the 
Cause  I  am  now  considering. 

I  have  compared  the  Observations  of  several  other  Stars,  and 
they  all  conspire  to  prove  that  the  Maximum  is  about  40"  or  41". 
I  will  therefore  suppose  that  it  is  40"^  or  (which  amounts  to  the 
same)  that  Light  moves,  or  is  propagated  as  far  as  from  the  Sun 
to  us  in  8'  13".  The  near  Agreement  which  I  met  with  among 
my  Observations  induces  me  to  think,  that  the  Maximum  (as  I  have 
here  fixed  it)  cannot  differ  so  much  as  a  Second  from  the  Truth, 
and  therefore  it  is  probable  that  the  Time  which  Light  spends  in 
passing  from  the  Sun  to  us,  may  be  determined  by  these  Obser- 
vations within  5"  or  10" ;  which  is  such  a  degree  of  exactness  as 
we  can  never  hope  to  attain  from  the  Eclipses  of  Jupiter's  Satel- 
lites. 

Having  thus  found  the  Maximum,  or  what  the  greatest  Alter- 
nation of  Declination  would  be  in  a  Star  placed  in  the  Pole  of  the 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 


28l 


Ecliptick,  I  will  now  deduce  from  it  (according  to  the  foregoing 
Hypothesis)  the  Alteration  of  Declination  in  one  or  two  Stars,  at 
such  times  as  they  were  actually  observed,  in  order  to  see  how  the 
Hypothesis  will  correspond  with  the  Phenomena  through  all  the 
Parts  of  the  Year. 

It  would  be  too  tedious  to  set  down  the  whole  Series  of  my 
Observations ;  I  will  therefore  make  Choice  only  of  such  as  are 
most  proper  for  my  present  Purpose,  and  will  begin  with  those  of 
v  Draconis. 

This  Star  appeared  farthest  North  about  September  7th,  1727, 
as  it  ought  to  have  done  according  to  my  Hypothesis.  The  follow- 
ing Table  shews  how  much  more  Southerly  the  star  was  found  to  be 
by  Observation  in  several  Parts  of  the  Year,  and  how  much  more 
Southerly  it  ought  to  be  according  to  the  Hypothesis. 


to 

to        °2 

to 

to        w 

0         fc 

o        55 

0         K 

O                    (Q 

8§g 

W         Hj         W 

«    0    g 

Sfc    O 
fe    §    H 

8  ^  « 

1§> 

g  g  rt 

5    H    S 

^  >  £ 

S  §  85 

ill 

W    Q    g 

to   §   ^ 

to   §   W 

§1 

g.I! 

«g§ 

w     B 

M      ^      W 

S  «  B 

1727  D. 

g    « 

B     « 

1728  D. 

B     S 

Oct.     20 

41 

4i 

Mar.    24 

37 

38 

Nov.   17 

m 

12 

April     6 

36 

361 

Dec.      6 

m 

18i 

May      6 

28i 

291 

Dec.    28 

25 

26 

June     5 

Itt 

20 

1728 

June    15 

171 

17 

Jan.     24 

34 

34 

July      3 

ii* 

111 

Feb.    10 

38 

37 

Aug.     2 

4 

4 

Mar.      7 

39 

39 

Sept.     6 

0 

0 

Hence  it  appears,  that  the  Hypothesis  corresponds  with  the  Ob- 
servations of  this  Star  through  all  Parts  of  the  Year;  for  the  small 
Differences  between  them  seem  to  arise  from  the  Uncertainty  of 
the  Observations,  which  is  occasioned  (as  I  imagine)  chiefly  by 
the  tremulous  or  undulating  Motion  of  the  Air,  and  of  the  Vapours 
in  it;  which  causes  the  Stars  sometimes  to  dance  to  and  fro,  so 
much  that  it  is  difficult  to  judge  when  they  are  exactly  on  the 
Middle  of  the  Wire  that  is  fixed  in  the  common  Focus  of  the 
Glasses  of  the  Telescope. 

I  must  confess  to  you,  that  the  Agreement  of  the  Observations 


282 


THE  MONIST. 


with  each  other,  as  well  as  with  the  Hypothesis,  is  much  greater 
than  I  expected  to  find,  before  I  had  compared  them;  and  it  may 
possibly  be  thought  to  be  too  great,  by  those  who  have  been  used 
to  Astronomical  Observations,  and  know  how  difficult  it  is  to  make 
such  as  are  in  all  respects  exact.  But  if  it  would  be  any  Satisfaction 
to  such  Persons  (till  I  have  an  Opportunity  of  describing  my  In- 
strument and  the  manner  of  using  it)  I  could  assure  them,  that  in 
above  70  Observations  which  I  made  of  this  Star  in  a  Year,  there 
is  but  one  (and  that  is  noted  as  very  dubious  on  account  of  Clouds) 
which  differs  from  the  foregoing  Hypothesis  more  than  2",  and  this 
does  not  differ  3". 

This  therefore  being  the  Fact,  I  cannot  but  think  it  very  prob- 
able, that  the  Phenomena  proceed  from  the  Cause  I  have  assigned, 
since  the  foregoing  Observations  make  it  sufficiently  evident,  that 
the  Effect  of  the  real  Cause,  whatever  it  is,  varies  in  this  Star,  in 
the  same  Proportion  that  it  ought  according  to  the  Hypothesis. 

But  least  v  Draconis  may  be  thought  not  so  proper  to  shew  the 
proportion,  in  which  the  apparent  alteration  of  Declination  is  in- 
creased or  diminished,  as  those  Stars  which  lie  near  the  Equinoctial 
Colure:  I  will  give  you  also  the  Comparison  between  the  Hypoth- 
esis and  the  Observations  of  -^  Ursa  Majoris,  that  which  was  far- 
thest South  about  the  17th  Day  of  January  1728,  agreable  to  the 
Hypothesis.  The  following  Table  shews  how  much  more  Northerly 


to        w 

to 

to        « 

0          fc 

0    g 

s  § 

o       55 

w  &  o 

«    fc    8 

^       55       M 

g    0    H 

O      Q      W 

CJ      Q      £3 

y  o  £j 

«  §  2 

w  S  |S 

i  g  I 

w  fc  ^ 

w  fc  > 

H      fc      ^ 

w  S  S 

to    J3    £ 

to   §   B 

i  a  1 

i  a  w 

p  w  o 

MOW 

§  a  § 

S  «  g 

u  a  x 

w    0    H 

M      0      fx 

y    ®    H 

1727  d. 

w      « 

B     S 

1728  d. 

3     « 

g     S 

Sept.  14 

29* 

28* 

April  16 

18* 

18 

Sept.  24 

24* 

25* 

May      5 

24* 

23* 

Oct.     16 

19* 

19* 

June     5 

32 

31* 

Nov.   11 

11* 

10* 

June   25 

35 

34* 

Dec.    14 

4 

3 

July    17 

36 

36 

1728 

Aug.     2 

35 

35* 

Feb.    17 

2 

3 

Sept.  20 

26* 

26* 

Mar.    21 

11* 

10* 

CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  283 

it  was  found  by  Observation  in  several  Parts  of  the  Year,  and  also 
what  the  Difference  should  have  been  according  to  the  Hypothesis. 

I  find  upon  Examination,  that  the  Hypothesis  agrees  altogether 
as  exactly  with  the  Observations  of  this  Star,  as  the  former;  for  in 
about  50  that  were  made  of  it  in  a  Year,  I  do  not  meet  with  a 
Difference  of  so  much  as  2",  except  in  one,  which  is  mark'd  as  doubt- 
ful on  Account  of  the  Undulation  of  the  Air  &c.  And  this  does  not 
differ  3"  from  the  Hypothesis. 

The  agreement  between  the  Hypothesis  and  the  Observations 
of  this  Star  is  the  more  to  be  reguarded,  since  it  proves  that  the 
Alteration  of  Declination,  on  account  of  the  Precession  of  the  Equi- 
nox, is  (as  I  before  supposed)  regular  thro'  all  Parts  of  the  Years; 
so  far  at  least,  as  not  to  occasion  a  Difference  great  enough  to  be 
discovered  with  this  Instrument.  It  likewise  proves  the  other  part 
of  my  former  Supposition,  viz.  that  the  annual  Alteration  of  Decli- 
nation in  Stars  near  the  Equinoctial  Colure,  is  at  this  Time  greater 
than  a  Precession  of  50"  would  occasion :  for  this  Star  was  20"  more 
Southerly  in  September  1728,  than  in  September  1727,  that  is,  about 
2"  more  than  it  would  have  been,  if  the  Precession  was  but  50". 
But  I  may  hereafter,  perhaps,  be  better  able  to  determine  this  Point, 
from  my  Observations  of  those  Stars  that  lie  near  the  Equinoctial 
Colure,  at  about  the  same  Distance  from  the  North  Pole  of  the 
Equator,  and  nearly  opposite  in  right  Ascension. 

I  think  it  needless  to  give  you  the  Comparison  between  the 
Hypothesis  and  the  Observations  of  any  more  Stars ;  since  the  Agree- 
ment in  the  foregoing  is  a  kind  of  Demonstration  (whether  it  be 
allowed  that  I  have  discovered  the  real  Cause  of  the  Phenomena  or 
not;)  that  the  Hypothesis  gives  at  least  the  true  Law  of  the  Varia- 
tion of  Declination  in  different  Stars,  with  Respect  to  their  differ- 
ent Situations  and  Aspects  with  the  Sun.  And  if  this  is  the  Case, 
it  must  be  granted,  that  the  Parallax  of  the  fixt  Stars  is  much 
smaller,  than  hath  been  hitherto  supposed  by  those  who  have  pre- 
tended to  deduce  it  from  their  Observations.  I  believe,  that  I  may 
venture  to  say,  that  in  either  of  the  two  Stars,  last  mentioned,  it 
does  not  amount  to  2".  I  am  of  Opinion,  that  if  it  were  1",  I  should 
have  perceived  it,  in  the  great  number  of  Observations  that  I  made 
especially  of  v  Draconis;  which  agreeing  with  the  Hypothesis  (with- 
out allowing  anything  for  Parallax)  nearly  as  well  when  the  Sun 
was  in  Conjunction  with,  as  in  Opposition  to,  this  Star,  it  seems 
very  probable  that  the  Parallax  of  it  is  not  so  great  as  one  single 


284  THE  MONIST. 

Second ;  and  Consequently  that  it  is  above  400000  times  farther  from 
us  than  the  Sun. 

There  appearing  therefore  after  all,  no  sensible  Parallax  in  the 
fixt  Stars,  the  Anti-Co  pernicans  have  still  room  on  that  Account, 
to  object  against  the  Motion  of  the  Earth;  and  they  may  have  (if 
they  please)  a  much  greater  objection  against  the  Hypothesis,  by 
which  I  have  endeavoured  to  solve  the  fore-mentioned  Phenomena; 
by  denying  the  progressive  Motion  of  Light,  as  well  as  that  of  the 
Earth. 

But  as  I  do  not  apprehend,  that  either  of  these  Postulates  will 
be  denied  me  by  the  Generality  of  the  Astronomers  and  Philosophers 
of  the  present  Age;  so  I  shall  not  doubt  of  obtaining  their  Assent 
to  the  Consequences  which  I  have  deduced  from  them;  if  they  are 
such  as  have  the  Approbation  of  so  great  a  Judge  of  them  as  Your- 
self. I  am 

Sir,  Your  most  Obedient 

Humble  Servant 

J.  BRADLEY. 
POSTSCRIPT. 

As  to  the  Observations  of  Dr.  Hook,  I  must  own  to  you,  that 
before  Mr.  Molyneux's  Instrument  was  erected,  I  had  no  small 
opinion  of  their  Correctness;  the  Length  of  his  Telescope  and  the 
Care  he  pretends  to  have  taken  in  making  them  exact,  having  been 
strong  Inducements  with  me  to  think  them  so.  And  Since  I  have 
been  convinced  both  from  Mr.  Molyneux's  Observations  and  my 
own,  that  the  Doctor's  are  really  very  far  from  being  either  exact 
or  agreeable  to  the  Phenomena;  I  am  greatly  at  a  loss  how  to  ac- 
count for  it.  I  cannot  well  conceive  that  an  Instrument  of  the 
Length  of  36  Feet,  constructed  in  the  Manner  he  describes  his, 
could  have  been  liable  to  an  Error  of  near  30"  (which  was  doubtless 
the  Case)  if  rectified  with  so  much  Care  as  he  represents. 

The  Observations  of  Mr.  Flamsteed  of  the  different  Distances 
of  the  Pole  Star  from  the  Pole  at  different  Times  of  the  Year, 
which  were  through  Mistake  looked  upon  by  some  as  a  Proof  of  the 
annual  Parallax  of  it,  seem  to  have  been  made  with  much  greater 
Care  than  those  of  Dr.  Hook.  For  though  they  do  not  all  exactly 
correspond  with  each  other,  yet  from  the  whole  Mr.  Flamsteed  con- 
cluded that  the  Star  was  35"  40"  or  45"  nearer  the  Pole  in  December 
than  in  May  or  July :  and  according  to  my  Hypothesis  it  ought  to 
appear  40"  nearer  in  December  than  in  June.  The  Agreement  there- 
fore of  the  Observations  with  the  Hypothesis  is  greater  than  could 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  285 

reasonably  be  expected,  considering  the  Radius  of  the  Instrument, 
and  the  Manner  in  which  it  was  constructed. 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  LEAST  ACTION.* 

REMARKS  ON  SOME  PASSAGES  IN  MACHOS  MECHANICS. 

Ernst  Mach  in  his  Mechanics1  remarks,2  with  reference  to  the 
integral  variational  principles  of  Hamilton  and  of  least  action,  that 
other  such  principles  are  possible,  which  idea  has  been  suggestive  to 
myselfy  and,  as  I  have  obtained  some  results  which  throw  light  on 
Mach's  suggestions,  I  will  try  to  describe  the  results  here  in  not  too 
technical  language.3 

i. 

We  must  first  of  all  notice  a  slight  historical  inexactitude  in 
Mach's  treatment  of  the  principle  of  least  action.  "Maupertuis," 
we  are  told,*  "enunciated,  in  1747,  a  principle  which  he  called  lle 
principe  de  la  moindre  quantite  d 'action.' '''  Maupertuiss  laid  before 
the  Paris  Academy  on  April  15,  1744,  a  memoir  in  which  he  ex- 
plained the  reflection  and  refraction  of  light  by  a  hypothesis  sub- 
stituted for  Fermat's  principle  of  least  time.6 

Maupertuis,  like  a  good  follower  of  Newton,  accepted  the  emis- 
sion hypothesis  of  light,  and,  according  to  P.  Stackel,7  the  contra- 

*  Philip  E.  B.  Jourdain,  an  English  scholar  who  has  devoted  his  life  to 
research  in  the  line  of  modern  logic,  mathematics  and  pure  mechanics,  sub- 
mits to  us  some  remarks  on  Mach's  Science  of  Mechanics.    He  is  a  devoted 
and  zealous  student  of  Mach's  works  and  is  as  familiar  with  them  as  a  theo- 
logian with  his  Bible.     Being  also  well  acquainted  with  the  work  of  Georg 
Cantor,   Peano  and   Bertrand  Russell  he  is  especially  fitted  to  explain  the 
theoretical  aspect  of  pure  mechanics.     We  are  confident  that  his  lucubrations 
serve  a  good  purpose  and  therefore  deem  it  wise  to  submit  them  to  specialists 
by  giving  them  space  in  our  columns. 

1  Die  Mechanik  in  Hirer  Entwickelung  historisch-kritisch  dargestellt,  4th 
ed.,  Leipsic,  1901,  pp.  395-413;  Engl.  transl.  by  T.  J.  McCormack  under  the 
title  The  Science  of  Mechanics,  a  Critical  and  Historical  Account  of  its  Devel- 
opment, 3d  ed.,  Chicago,  1907,  pp.  364-380.  (This  translation  will  be  referred 
to  as  Mechanics,  and  the  above  German  edition  as  Mechanik.) 

'Mechanik,  pp.  399,  402,  413;  Mechanics,  pp.  368-369,  371-372,  380. 

8  Cf.  note  on  p.  78  of  my  paper  "On  the  General  Equations  of  Mechanics," 
Quarterly  Journal  of  Mathematics,  1904,  pp.  61-79. 

*  Mechanik,  p.  395 ;  Mechanics,  p.  364. 

*  Cf .  Mechanik,  pp.  484-485 ;  Mechanics,  pp.  454-455. 

6  Mechanik,  pp.  454-457  ',  Mechanics,  pp.  422-425. 

7  Encykl.  der  math.  Wiss.,  IV,  I,  (1908),  p.  49,  note  125.    Stackel  wrongly 
refers  to  the  Berlin  Mem.,  1745,  p.  276,  for  Maupertuis's  application  of  the 
principle  of  least  action  to  the  motion  of  light. 


286  THE  MONIST. 

diction  that  Mach  found  in  Maupertuis's  application  of  the  principle 
of  least  action  to  the  motion  of  light  is  due  to  Mach's  mistaken  sup- 
position that  Maupertuis  worked  on  the  basis  of  the  undulatory 
theory. 

On  Fermat's  principle  of  least  time  and  Maupertuis's  principle 
of  least  action,  we  will  quote  some  passages  from  E.  T.  Whittaker's 
lately  published  book,  A  History  of  the  Theories  of  Aether  and 
Electricity  from  the  Age  of  Descartes  to  the  Close  of  the  Nineteenth 
Century.8 

"Descartes's  theory  of  light  rapidly  displaced  the  conceptions 
which  had  held  sway  in  the  Middle  Ages.  The  validity  of  his  ex- 
planation of  refraction  was,  however,  called  in  question  by  his 
fellow-countryman  Pierre  de  Fermat  (b.  1601,  d.  1665),  and  a 
controversy  ensued  which  was  kept  up  by  the  Cartesians  long  after 
the  death  of  their  master.  Fermat^  eventually  introduced  a  new 
fundamental  law,  from  which  he  proposed  to  deduce  the  paths  of 
rays  of  light.  This  was  the  celebrated  Principle  of  Least  Time, 
enunciated I0in  the  form,  'Nature  always  acts  by  the  shortest  course.' 
From  it  the  law  of  reflection  can  readily  be  derived,  since  the  path 
described  by  light  between  a  point  on  the  incident  ray  and  a  point 
on  the  reflected  ray  is  the  shortest  possible  consistent  with  the  con- 
dition of  meeting  the  reflecting  surfaces.11  In  order  to  obtain  the 
law  of  refraction,  Fermat  assumed  that  'the  resistance  of  the  media 
is  different/  and  applied  his  'method  of  maxima  and  minima'  to 
find  the  paths  which  would  be  described  in  the  least  time  from  a 
point  of  one  medium  to  a  point  of  the  other.  In  1661  he  arrived 
at  the  solution.12  'The  result  of  my  work/  he  writes,  'has  been  the 
most  extraordinary,  the  most  unforeseen  and  the  happiest,  that  ever 
was;  for,  after  having  performed  all  the  equations,  multiplications, 
antitheses  and  other  operations  of  my  method,  and  having  finally 
finished  the  problem,  I  have  found  that  my  principle  gives  exactly 
and  precisely  the  same  proportion  for  the  refractions  which  Monsieur 

'London  and  Dublin,  1910,  pp.  9-11,  102-103. 

0  Renati  Descartes  Epistolae,  Pars  tertia;  Amsterdam,  1683.  The  Fermat 
correspondence  is  comprised  in  letters  xxix  to  xlvi. 

10  Epist.  xlii,  written  at  Toulouse  in  August,  1657,  to  Monsieur  de  la  Cham- 
bre;  reprinted  in  (Euvres  de  Fermat  (ed.  1891),  Vol.  II,  p.  354. 

"That  reflected  light  follows  the  shortest  path  was  no  new  result,  for  it 
had  been  affirmed  (and  attributed  to  Hero  of  Alexandria)  in  the  /ce^rfXcua 
ruv  ATTTIKUV  of  Heliodorus  of  Larissa,  a  work  of  which  several  editions  were 
published  in  the  seventeenth  century. 

"  Epist.  xliii,  written  at  Toulouse  on  Jan.  i,  1662 ;  reprinted  in  (Euvres  de 
Fermat,  Vol.  II,  p.  457;  Vol.  I,  pp.  170,  173. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  287 

Descartes  has  established.'  His  surprise  was  all  the  greater,  as  he 
had  supposed  light  to  move  more  slowly  in  dense  than  in  rare  media, 
whereas  Descartes  had  (as  will  be  evident  from  the  demonstration 
given  above)  been  obliged  to  make  the  contrary  supposition. 

"Although  Fermat's  result  was  correct,  and,  indeed,  of  high 
permanent  interest,  the  principles  from  which  it  was  derived  were 
metaphysical  rather  than  physical  in  character,  and  consequently 
were  of  little  use  for  the  purpose  of  framing  a  mechanical  explana- 
tion of  light.  Descartes's  theory  therefore  held  the  field  until  the 
publication  in  1667*3  of  the  Micrographia  of  Robert  Hooke  (b.  1635, 
d.  1703),  one  of  the  founders  of  the  Royal  Society,  and  at  one  time 
its  Secretary." 

Further  on,  we  read  (p.  102)  :  "  ----  the  echoes  of  the  old  con- 
troversy between  Descartes  and  Fermat  about  the  law  of  refraction 
were  awakened  '*  by  Pierre  Louis  Moreau  de  Maupertuis  (b.  1698, 
d.  1759). 

"It  will  be  remembered  that  according  to  Descartes  the  velocity 
of  light  is  greatest  in  dense  media,  while  according  to  Fermat  the 
propagation  is  swiftest  in  free  ether.  The  arguments  of  the  cor- 
puscular theory  convinced  Maupertuis  that  on  this  particular  point 
Descartes  was  in  the  right;  but  nevertheless  he  wished  to  retain 
for  science  the  beautiful  method  by  which  Fermat  had  derived  his 
result.  This  he  now  proposed  to  do  by  modifying  Fermat's  prin- 
ciple so  as  to  make  it  agree  with  the  corpuscular  theory  ;  instead  of 
assuming  that  light  follows  the  quickest  path,  he  supposed  that  'the 
path  described  is  that  by  which  the  quantity  of  action  is  the  least'; 
and  this  action  he  defined  to  be  proportional  to  the  sum  of  the  spaces 
described,  each  multiplied  by  the  velocity  with  which  it  is  traversed. 
Thus  instead  of  Fermat's  expression 


(where  t  denotes  time,  v  velocity,  and  ds  an  element  of  the  path) 
Maupertuis  introduced 

Jv.ds 

as  the  quantity  which  is  to  assume  its  minimum  value  when  the 

path  of  integration  is  the  actual  path  of  light.    Since  Maupertuis's  v, 

which  denotes  the  velocity  according  to  the  corpuscular  theory,  is 

"The  imprimatur  of  Viscount  Brouncker,  P.R.S.,  is  dated  Nov.  23,  1664. 

14  Mem.  de  I'Acad.,  1744,  PP-  417-426  [or  (Euvres  de  Mr.  de  Maupertuis,  Vol. 
IV,  Lyons,  1756,  pp.  3-18.  To  Maupertuis's  work  we  will  return  on  another 
occasion]. 


288  THE  MONIST. 

proportional  to  the  reciprocal  of  Fermat's  v,  which  denotes  the  veloc- 
ity according  to  the  wave-theory,  the  two  expressions  are  really 
equivalent,  and  lead  to  the  same  law  of  refraction.  Maupertuis's 
memoir  is,  however,  of  great  interest  from  the  point  of  view  of 
dynamics ;  for  his  suggestion  was  subsequently  developed  by  himself 
and  by  Euler  and  Lagrange  into  a  general  principle  which  covers 

the  whole  range  of  nature,  so  far  as  nature  is  a  dynamical  system/' 

*       *       * 

In  a  memoir  of  1746,Z5  Maupertuis  extended  his  hypothesis 
to  all  motions  and  called  it  the  universal  principle  of  rest  and  mo- 
tion. By  way  of  proving  it,  he  derived  the  known  laws  of  impact 
of  inelastic  and  elastic  bodies,  and  of  the  lever  ;l6  the  motion  of  light 
having  been  dealt  with  in  the  memoir  of  1744.  It  is  most  important 
to  realize  that,  as  A.  Mayer1?  pointed  out,  Euler's  discovery,  made 
under  the  stimulus  of  the  Bernoullis  and  published  in  the  autumn 
of  1744  in  an  appendix  to  his  Methodus  inveniendi,  was  independent 
of  Maupertuis,  but  that  later  on  Euler's  own  tendency  towards 
metaphysical  speculation  and  the  influence  of  Maupertuis  combined 
to  make  Euler  treat  his  principle  in  a  less  precise  and  more  general 
way. 

ii. 

Euler  observed  in  1744  that  the  differential  equations  of  the 
motion  of  a  particle  are  given  by  the  simple  requirement  that  the 
integral  fv.ds,  where  for  the  velocity  v  is  substituted  its  value 
resulting  from  the  principle  of  vis  viva,  and  the  integral  is  taken 
between  two  positions  of  the  particle,  should  be  a  minimum.  Euler 

15  "Les  loix  du  mouvement  et  du  repos  deduites  d'un  principe  metaphysique." 
Mem.  de  VAcad.  de  Berlin,  1746,  pp.  267-294.    Vpss  (Encykl.  der  math.  Wiss., 
IV,  i,  p.  95,  note  256)  has  1745  as  the  date  of  this  memoir.    This  memoir  was 
that  analyzed  by  Mach  (Mechanik,  pp.  395-397;  Mechanics,  pp.  364-367).   The 
analogies  that  exist  between  the  motion  of  masses  and  the  motion  of  light, 
which  were  noticed  by  Johann  Bernoulli  and  by  Mobius,  were  dealt  with  by 
Mach  (Mechanik,  pp.  402-408,  410-413,  457-459;  Mechanics,  pp.  372-380,  425- 
427).    The  principle  of  least  action  has  been  found  very  useful  in  optics,  by 
Laplace,  for  example,  in  the  treatment  of  astronomical  refractions;  and  the 
mathematics  of  the  theory  of  systems  of  rays  built  upon  this  one  principle, 
which  was  the  earliest  work  of  William  Rowan  Hamilton,  were  later  (in  1834 
and  1835)  transferred  by  Hamilton  to  the  general  problem  of  dynamics.    Cf. 
P.  Stackel,  Encykl  der  math.  Wiss.,  IV,  i,  1908,  pp.  489-493. 

16  In  a  memoir  called  "Loi  du  repos  des  corps"  (Mem.  de  I'Acad.  de  Paris, 
1740,  pp.  170-176;  CEuvres,  Vol.  IV,  pp.  45-63)  Maupertuis  remarked  that  the 
work  done  when  a  final  configuration  of  equilibrium  is  reached  is  generally 
either  a  maximum  or  a  minimum  (see  Mach,  Mechanik,  pp.  69-75 ;  Mechanics, 
pp.  68-73). 

"Geschichte  des  Prinzips  der  kleinsten  Aktion,  Akademische  Antritts- 
vorlesung,  Leipsic,  1877 ;  cf.  my  notes  in  Ostwald's  Klassiker,  No.  167,  pp.  31-37- 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  289 

expressly  emphasized,  first,  that  his  theorem  only  holds  if  the  prin- 
ciple of  vis  viva  holds  (and  therefore  cannot  hold  for  motion  in  a 
resisting  medium),  and,  secondly,  that  we  must  express  v  in  terms 
of  the  attracting  forces  by  quantities  belonging  to  the  orbit.18 

Euler's  work  on  this  point  was  influenced  adversely  by  his  own 
tendency  toward  metaphysical  speculation  and  Maupertuis's  dis- 
covery— published  some  months  before  Euler's — of  the  obscure  and 
almost  theological  universal  "principle  of  the  least  quantity  of  ac- 
tion."1* 

in. 

Lagrange20  generalized  Euler's  theorem  for  the  motion  of  any 
system  of  masses  in  the  following  way: 

Let  mlt  m2,  mst.  . .  be  masses  which  act  upon  one  another  in  any 
manner,  and  also,  if  we  wish,  move  under  the  influence  of  any 
central  forces  which  are  proportional  to  any  functions  of  the  dis- 
tances;  let  slt  s2,  s3,.  . .  be  the  spaces  which  are  described  by  these 
masses  in  the  time  t,  and  let  z\,  vz,  v3,. . .  be  their  velocities  at  the 
end  of  this  time ;  then21 

Sw.  §v.ds 

is  a  maximum  or  minimum,  and  thus,  by  the  principles  of  the  cal- 
culus of  variations, 

2m.f(Sv.ds  +  v.8ds)  =  0 (1) 

Lagrange  eliminated  the  terms  involving  Sv  by  making  use  of 
the  equation 

18Jacobi  (see  below),  by  direct  generalization  of  Euler's  theorem,  reached 
his  theorem. 

"  The  early  history  of  the  principle  of  least  action  is  very  fully  dealt  with 
by  me  in  my  notes  at  the  end  of  Ostwald's  Klassiker  der  exakten  Wissen- 
schaften,  No.  167. 

""Application  de  la  methode  exposee  dans  le  memoire  precedent  a  la 
solution  de  differents  problemes  de  dynamique,"  Miscellanea  Taurinensia  for 
1760  and  1761,  Vol.  II,  pp.  196-298 ;  (Euvres  de  Lagrange,  Vol.  I,  pp.  365-468. 
This  memoir  immediately  followed  Lagrange's  first  fundamental  memoir  on 
the  calculus  of  variations:  "Essai  d'une  nouvelle  methode  pour  determiner 
les  maxima  et  les  minima  des  formules  integrates  indefinies,"  Misc.  Taur., 
1760  and  1761  [published  1762],  Vol.  II,  pp.  173-195;  (Euvres,  Vol.  I,  pp.  335- 
362;  Ostivald's  Klassiker  der  exakten  IVissenschaften,  No.  47,  pp.3~3O. 

In  Lagrange's  first  publication  ("Recherches  sur  la  methode  de  maximis 
et  minimis,"  Misc.  Taur.  for  1759,  Vol.  I;  (Euvres,  Vol.  I,  pp.  3-20),  he  an- 
nounced (p.  15)  his  intention  of  deriving  the  whole  of  mechanics,  by  means 
of  the  principle  of  the  least  quantity  of  action,  from  a  method  he  had  of  in- 
vestigating the  maxima  and  minima  of  indefinite  integral  formulae. 

a  For  convenience  of  printing,  the  suffixes  to  the  2,  m,  v,  and  s  are  here 
omitted.  Instead  of  the  now  more  usual  S  Lagrange  (see  below)  used  S. 


2QO  THE  MONIST. 

2m.v.8v  =  SU  .....................  (2) 

got  by  varying  (differentiating  with  8)  the  equation  of  vis  viva. 

Thus  the  equation  (1),  in  conjunction  with  the  condition  (2), 
supposing  that  all  the  positions  at  the  limits  of  the  integral  are  given, 
so  that  there  the  variations  of  the  coordinates  are  zero,22  gives  the 
fundamental  equation^ 


JSdm{  (d+Hdt)Bx  +  .  .  .!  =0,  •  •  (3) 

where  118*  +  .  .  .  =  8U, 

and  S  is  a  sign  of  a  definite  integral  which  refers  to  the  masses  of 
the  system  ;  so  that,  if  there  are  a  finite  number  of  masses  m±,  m2, 
w3,..  ., 

Sdm  =  2m. 

If  there  is  an  equation  of  condition  <f>  =  0  between  the  coordinates, 
the  equation  8<£  =  0  gives  a  relation  between  the  8*'s_,  83^5  and  8,2's 
of  (3)  ;  and  then  we  can  eliminate  from  (3)  all  of  the  variations 
except  a  certain  number  which  is  the  degree  of  freedom  of  the  sys- 
tem. If,  then,  we  put  the  coefficient  of  every  independent  variation 
equal  to  zero,  we  obtain  the  necessary  number  of  differential  equa- 
tions for  the  solution  of  the  problem. 

An  important  point  is  that,  as  Holder2*  remarked,  Lagrange25 
drew  attention  to  the  fact  that,  even  when  the  expression  for  the 
element  of  work  is  not  a  complete  differential,  and  consequently 
"8U"  can  only  be  regarded  as  an  abbreviation,  and  not  as  a  notation 
for  the  variation  of  a  force-function,  that  the  formula  (2),  or 

8T  =  8U, 

can  be  applied  to  get  an  extension  of  the  principle  of  least  action 
even  to  non-conservative  forces.  This  wider  form  was  not  treated 
in  Lagrange's  later  work  in  the  Mecanique  analytique  on  the  prin- 
ciple of  least  action. 

Thus  Mach26  is  mistaken  in  stating  that  Lagrange  "drew  ex- 
press attention  to  the  fact  that  Euler's  principle  is  applicable  only 
in  cases  in  which  the  principle  of  vis  viva  holds."  Euler  had  already 
made  this  remark,  and  subsequently  Jacobi  strongly  emphasized  it; 
but  Lagrange,  correctly,  as  we  now  know,  first  drew  attention  to 

83  (Euvres,  Vol.  I,  pp.  369-370. 
*/«&,  pp.  368,  406,  418,  435,  459- 

84  Gott.  Nachr.,  1896,  p.  136.    In  Ostwald's  Klassiker,  No.  167,  last  line  on 
p.  39,  for  "Helmholtz"  read  "Holder." 

88  (Euvres,  Vol.  I,  pp.  384-385. 

86  Mechank,  p.  401  ;  Mechanics,  p.  371. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

the  fact  that  the  principle  of  least  action,  in  the  very  general  form 
which  he  gave  it,  does  not  depend  for  its  validity  on  that  principle 
of  vis  viva,  which  only  follows  from  the  general  equations  of  mechan- 
ics under  special  conditions. 

There  was  no  mention  of  this  extension  in  Lagrange's  later 
works,  and  Hamilton,  for  example,  only  took  from  Lagrange  the 
narrower  form  of  the  principle  of  least  action  which  was  given  in 

the  Mecanique. 

*       *       * 

Lagrange  appears  to  have  noticed  that  the  integrand  of  (3),  put 
equal  to  zero,  is  an  expression  of  d'Alembert's  principle;  and,  in 
that  form,  d'Alembert's  principle  is  the  fundamental  formula  of 
Lagrange's  analytical  mechanics,27  and  then  the  principle  of  least 
action  became,  for  Lagrange,  merely  a  result  of  the  laws  of  mechan- 
ics, to  be  got  by  the  integration  of  the  simpler  equation. 

However,  in  the  early  memoir  Lagrange  had  concluded  from 
his  generalized  principle  of  least  action  nearly  all  the  great  results 
which  later,  in  his  Mecanique,  he  derived  in  another  way;  and  so 
Jacobi28  remarked  that  Lagrange's  principle  became  the  mother  of 
our  whole  analytical  mechanics. 2$ 

87  D'Alembert's  principle  in  combination  with  the  principle  of  virtual  dis- 
placements appeared  in  the  above  variational  form  for  the  first  time  in  a 
prize  essay  of  1764  of  Lagrange's  on  the  libration  of  the  moon  (CEuvres,  Vol. 
VI,  pp.  5-61)  ;  and  then,  more  fully,  in  a  memoir  of  1780  (CEuvres,  Vol.  V.,  pp. 
5-122). 

The  various  editions  of  Lagrange's  Mecanique  are:  Mecanique  analitique, 
Paris  1788,  I  vol.;  second,  greatly  enlarged  edition,  Mecanique  analytique, 
Paris,  Vol.  I,  1811,  Vol.  II  (posthumous),  1815;  third  edition,  with  notes  by 
J.  Bertrand,  2  vols.,  Paris,  1853  and  1855 ;  fourth  edition,  after  the  third,  but 
with  additional  notes  by  G.  Darboux,  in  (Euvres  de  Lagrange,  Vols.  XI,  and 
XII,  Paris,  1888  and  1889. 

38  See  Compt.  Rend.,  Vol.  V,  1837,  pp.  61-67  (Ges.  Werke,  Vol.  iy,  .pp. 
129-136)  ;  Vorlesungen  uber  Dynamik,  gehalten  an  der  Universit'dt  zu  Konigs- 
berg  im  Winter  semester  1842-1843  und  nach  einem  von  C.  W.  Borchardt 
ausgearbeiteten  Hefte  herausgegeben  von  A.  Clebsch,  Berlin,  1866,  p.  2  (2d 
ed.,  revised  by  E.  Lottner,  in  Jacobi's  Ges.  Werke,  Supplementband).  Cf.  A. 
Mayer,  Geschichte  des  Prinzips  der  klcinsten  Action,  Leipsic,  1877,  p.  26  (on 
Mayer's  errors  see  my  notes  in  Ostwald's  Klassiker,  No.  167). 

In  this  early  memoir  the  problems  treated  by  Lagrange  were :  the  motion 
of  one  body  attracted  by  many  fixed  central  forces ;  general  problem  of  many 
attracting  masses  under  any  other  forces;  the  finding  of  the  orbits  of  two 
attracting  bodies  with  respect  to  a  third;  a  body  in  a  plane  under  forces  and 
drawing  two  other  bodies  by  threads;  a  thread  fixed  at  one  end  and  charged 
with  as  many  heavy  bodies  as  wished ;  an  inextensible  thread,  all  the  points  being 
under  any  forces;  the  same  problem  with  an  extensible  and  elastic  thread; 
motion  of  a  body  of  any  figure  animated  by  any  forces;  laws  of  the  motion 
of  non-elastic  and  elastic  fluids. 

28  However,  Lagrange's  method  of  multipliers  (Mach,  Mechanik,  pp.  499- 
500;  Mechanics,  p.  471)  appeared  first  in  the  Mechanique  analitique  of  1788. 


2Q2  THE  MONIST. 

After  the  publication  of  the  Mecanique,  the  principle  of  least 
action  fell  into  the  background  of  interest  until  Hamilton,  in  1834, 
showed  that  this  principle  had  also  a  totally  different  title  to  our 
consideration.  The  only  really  important  contribution  to  the  ex- 
ceedingly interesting  questions  that  rise  a  propos  of  the  principle 
of  least  action  was  an  almost  entirely  neglected  one  made  by  Olinde 
Rodrigues  in  1816. 


IV. 

In  Lagrange's  derivation,  the  variation  of  v(=ds/dt)  is  not 
carried  out,  but  the  terms  m.v.8v  are  eliminated  by  the  variational 
equation  obtained  from  the  principle  of  vis  viva.  Thus  it  is  not 
necessary  to  decide  whether  t  must  be  varied  or  not,  whether  we 
must  put 

a      d&s    dscfct         *      dBs 

OTJ  = or   Ov  = 

dt      dt  dt  dt' 

It  is  almost  beyond  doubt  that  Lagrange  would  have  maintained 
that  the  independent  variable  t  was  to  be  varied  ;3°  but  Rodrigues 
was  the  first  explicitly  to  say  that,  in  this  case,  t  must  be  varied. 

Lagrange  had  worked  with  a  space  integral  f^m.v.ds,  and  had 
only  remarked,  in  a  short  addition  to  the  section  on  the  principle  of 
least  action,  made  in  the  second  edition  of  the  Mecanique,  that  the 
above  space  integral  transforms  into  the  time -integral  fZT.dt, 
where  2T  is  the  vis  viva  (or,  as  we  now  say,  double  the  kinetic 
energy)  of  the  system.^1  But  Lagrange  did  not  actually  carry  out 
the  calculation  of  the  variation  of  this  time-integral ;  this  was  done 
by  Rodrigues.s2  Rodrigues,  as  E.  J.  Routhss  .did  later  and  appar- 
ently independently,  to  find  the  variation  of  fT.dt  under  the  con- 
dition T  =  U  +  const,  for  the  variation,  so  that  8T  -  8U  =  0,  multi- 
plied the  left-hand  side  of  this  last  equation  of  condition  by  an 
undetermined  factor,  integrated  it,  added  it  to  the  variation  of 
fT.dt,  put  all  equal  to  zero,  and  then  determined  the  factor. 

80  Cf.  (Euvres,  Vol.  I,  pp.  337,  345 ;  and  Ostwald's  Klassiker,  No.  167,  p.  56. 
"See  Ostwald's  Klassiker,  No.  167,  p.  n. 

M  Correspondance  sur  I'Ecole  polytech.,  Vol.  Ill,  1816,  pp.  159-162;  German 
translation,  with  notes  on  some  errors  of  Rodrigues,  in  Ostwald's  Klassiker, 
No.  167,  pp.  12-15,  41-42,  49-55- 

"First  in  An  Elementary  Treatise  on  the  Dynamics  of  a  System  of  Rigid 
Bodies,  3d  ed.,  London,  1877,  pp.  305-312,  560-562.  This  passage  coincides  in 
essentials  with  The  Advanced  Part  [Part  II]  of  a  Treatise  on  the  Dynamics 
of  a  System  of  Rigid  Bodies,  6th  ed.,  London,  1905,  pp.  301-309. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  2Q3 

V. 

The  question  as  to  whether  the  independent  variable  should  be 
varied  in  the  calculus  of  variations  is  of  great  importance  to  our 
conception  of  this  calculus.  According  to  Mach,  34  the  first  satis- 
factory explanation  of  the  meaning  of  the  process  of  variation  used 
in  this  calculus  was  given  by  J.  H.  Jellett.35  The  value  of  the 
function  y  =  <f>(x)  can  vary  by  an  (infinitesimal)  increment  dx  of 
the  independent  variable,  when  we  obtain  the  differential 


or  by  the  varying  of  the  form  </>  of  the  function  without  x  varying, 
so  that  <f>(x)  becomes 

^(^(K^+oAOO, 

where  \f/  is  an  arbitrary  function  and  c  is,  for  the  definition  of  an 
infinitesimal  variation,  an  infinitely  small  positive  number.  Then 
the  variation  of  y  is  defined  by 

*y  =  *i  (*)-*(*). 

Thus,  if  we  keep,  as  is  convenient,  the  term  "variation"  to  denote 
alterations  of  value  brought  about  by  alteration  of  the  form  alone 
of  the  function,  we  see  that  the  independent  variable  is  unaffected  by 
our  process  of  variation.  On  the  other  hand,  Lagrange,  as  we  have 
seen,  held  that  the  independent  variable  also  was  to  be  affected 
by  the  8  of  the  calculus  of  variations.  Indeed,  his  claim  that  his 
method  was  more  general  than  that  of  Euler  rested  partly  on  this 
ground.  But  other  mathematicians  appear  mostly  to  have  accepted 
that  conception  of  a  variation  which  Euler  gave  in  a  later  memoir 
on  Lagrange's  method,  that  a  "variation"  of  a  function  is  brought 
about  by  a  change  in  value  of  the  constants  occurring  in  that  function. 
Thus,  Jacobi,  in  his  Vorlesungen  uber  Dynamik?6  stated  that  the 
variations  8q  of  the  generalized  coordinates  q  contain  merely  the 
changes  in  value  of  the  #'s  which  arise  from  changes  in  value  of 
the  arbitrary  constants  occurring  in  the  q's.  Accordingly,  he  main- 
tained37  that  the  independent  variable  is  not  to  be  "varied,"  so  that 
Bt  =  0.38 

"Mechanik,  pp.  468-474;  Mechanics,  pp.  437-443. 

85  An  Elementary  Treatise  on  the  Calculus  of  Variations,  Dublin,  1850,  pp. 
i,  5-6.  Cf.  A.  Kneser,  Lehrbuch  der  Variationsrechnung,  Brunswick,  1900,  pp. 
1-2. 

88  Werke,  Supplementband,  p.  145. 

87  Ibid.,  pp.  50,  59,  146,  149. 

88  Cf.  similar  views  on  the  nature  of  a  "variation"  with  Euler,  Lagrange, 
Lacroix,  G.  W.  Strauch,  M.  Ohm,  Cauchy,  and  Stegmann  in  I.  Todhunter's 


294  THE  MONIST. 

So  Jacobi,  in  his  Vorlesungen  uber  Dynamik^  stated  that,  in 
the  action  integral  f'Sm.v.ds,  the  time  must  be  eliminated  by  the 
principle  of  vis  viva,  and  all  be  reduced  to  space-elements.  This, 
as  Mayer  remarked  in  his  tract  of  1877,  was  required  by  Euler  in 
the  case  considered  by  him.  Thus  JacobiV0  formulation  of  the 
principle  of  least  action  was:  If  two  positions  of  the  system  are 
given  (that  is  to  say,  if  we  know  the  values  which,  for  x  =  a  and 
#  =  &,  the  remaining  Zn-\  coordinates  receive),  and  we  extend  the 
integral 


2w  .  ds2 

to  the  whole  path  of  the  system  from  the  first  position  to  the  second, 
then  its  value  is  a  minimum  for  the  actual  path  as  compared  with  all 
possible  (consistent  with  the  conditions,  if  there  be  any,  of  the 
system)  paths.41 

Mayer,  in  his  tract  of  1877,*2  accepted  Jacobi's  view  that  8t  =  0 
and  consequently  that,  by  means  of  the  principle  of  vis  viva,  we 
must  reduce  all  the  quantities  in  the  integrand  to  quantities  which 
refer  to  the  path  of  the  system  ;  and  that  the  theorem  of  least  action 
without  this  condition  is  quite  meaningless.  Since  Lagrange  did 
not  eliminate  the  time,  Mayer*3  concluded  that  Lagrange's  theorem 
was  meaningless,  and  what  Lagrange  really  meant  by  his  theorem 
was  what  is  known  as  Hamilton's  principle.  This  view  had  been 
previously  maintained  by  M.  Ostrogradski.44 

But,  in  a  memoir  of  1886  on  the  general  theorems  of  the  cal- 
culus of  variations  which  correspond  to  the  two  forms  of  the  prin- 
ciple of  least  action  in  dynamics,  Mayer*s  remarked,  on  the  variation 

work  A  History  of  the  Progress  of  the  Calculus  of  Variations  During  the 
Nineteenth  Century,  Cambridge  and  London,  1861,  pp.  2,  8,  II,  13,  17-20,  31, 
377,  378,  402,  413,  480-481. 

89  Werke,  Supplementband,  p.  44  ;  Ostwald's  Klassiker,  No.  167,  p.  17  (on 
pp.  16-26  is  a  reprint  of  Jacobi's  sixth  and  part  of  his  seventh  lecture,  which 
relate  to  the  principle  of  least  action). 

40  Werke,  Supplementband,  p.  45  ;  Ostwald's  Klassiker,  No.  167,  p.  18  (cf. 
the  note  on  p.  55). 

"On  the  limitations  to  the  minimum-condition,  which  were  pointed  out 
by  Jacobi  (cf.  Mach,  Mechanik,  p.  401;  Mechanics,  p.  371)  see  Werke,  Suppl, 
pp.  45-49;  Klassiker,  No.  167,  pp.  18-22,  58. 

41  See  p.  24,  and  Klassiker,  No.  167,  p.  57. 
48  Op.  cit.,  p.  27. 

"Klassiker,  No.  167,  pp.  57-58. 

""Die  beiden  allgemeinen  Satze  der  Variationsrechnung,  welche  den 
beiden  Formen  des  Prinzips  der  kleinsten  Aktion  in  der  Dynamik  entsprechen," 
Berichte  der  math.-phys.  Classe  der  K'on.  Sachs.  Ges.  der  Wiss.  zu  Leipzig, 
Sitzung  am  14.  November  1886,  Vol.  XXXyill,  pp.  343-355-  The  first  person 
correctly  to  show  the  importance  of  Rodrigues's  memoir  was  Th.  Sloudsky 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  295 

of  t  with  Rodrigues :  "Now,  from  the  point  of  view  of  dynamics,  in 
which  we  only  permit  variations  from  the  instantaneous  position 
of  the  system  under  consideration,  that  is  so  very  unusual  that  I  did 
not  think  at  all  of  this  possibility  in  my  earlier  work.  But  as  soon 
as  we  neglect  a  purely  dynamical  signification  (Deutung),  and  vary, 
not  only  the  coordinates,  but  also  the  time,  immediately  that  point 
which  always  caused  the  greatest  doubts  in  Lagrange's  derivation 
becomes  clear.  It  is  explained,  namely,  how  the  equation  of  vis  viva, 
if  it  is  prescribed  as  an  equation  of  condition,  can  yet  leave  the 
variations  of  the  coordinates  quite  unlimited/6  and  we  see  then  that 
Jacobi's  assertion  that  we  must  necessarily  eliminate  the  time  from 
the  action-integral  by  means  of  the  theorem  of  vis  viva  is  not  so; 
that,  besides  Jacobi's  principle,  there  is  a  second,  equally  justified 
form  of  the  principle  of  least  action ;  and  that  it  is  this  second  form, 
and  not  Hamilton's  principle  inaccurately  formulated,  which  La- 
grange  proved  correctly,  though  certainly  not  with  his  usual  clear- 
ness. 

We  may  here  remark  that  Routh,*?  from  1877  onwards  and 
apparently  independently  of  Rodrigues,  also  varied  tf  "by  the  funda- 
mental theorem  in  the  calculus  of  variations,"  and  derived  the  prin- 
ciple of  least  action  as  Rodrigues  did. 

If  Ms  to  be  varied,  we  must  regard  it,  according  to  the  con- 
ception of  a  "variation"  derived  from  Jellett,  as  a  function  of  an- 
other variable,  0,  so  that  BO  =  0  but  8t  is  not  zero  in  general.  This 
was  done  explicitly  by  Helmholtz*8  in  1887. 

Helmholtz  also  stated  the  view  that  Hamilton's  principle  is  a 
form  of  Lagrange's  principle.  The  grounds  for  this  view  are,  as 
I  showed  in  1908,49  more  clearly  evidenced  in  an  identity  established 
by  Rethy  under  certain  restrictions. 

VI. 

We  have  dealt  with  the  question  as  to  the  relation  of  the  prin- 
ciple of  least  action  to  Hamilton's  principle,  and  we  have  seen  how 
Lagrange,  by  working  with  a  form  which  only  contained  the  time 
through  the  velocities,  and  in  which  the  variations  of  the  velocities 

(1866)  ;  Bertrand,  in  his  notes  on  Lagrange's  Mtcanique,  mentioned  Rodrigues, 
but  put  S(dq/dt)  =d8q/dt. 

**  Cf.  Klassiker,  No.  167,  pp.  43-44. 

47  Cf.  ibid.,  pp.  50-51. 

*""Zur  Geschichte  des  Prinzips  der  kleinsten  Aktion,"  Sitzungsber.  der 
Berliner  Akad.,  Sitzung  vom  10.  Marz  1887,  pp.  225-236;  Wiss.  Abh.,  Vol.  Ill, 
pp.  249-263. 

"Math.  Ann.,  Vol.  LXV,  pp.  514-516. 


296  THE  MONIST. 

could  be  at  once  eliminated  by  means  of  the  varied  equation  of  vis 
viva,  allowed  it  to  remain  doubtful  whether  t  was  to  be  varied  in 
the  principle  of  least  action,  or  not.  We  have  seen  how  this  question 
has  given  rise  to  discussions  and  misunderstandings  which  are  con- 
nected with  the  principle  of  the  calculus  of  variations,  in  the  works 
of  Rodrigues,  Jacobi,  Ostrogradski,  Routh,  Mayer,  Sloudsky,  Ber- 
trand,  Helmholtz,  and  Rethy.  We  have  seen,  finally,  that  Lagrange 
had  attained  to  a  very  general  formulation  of  the  principle  of  least 
action,  in  which  the  equation  of  vis  viva  does  not  hold,  a  force-func- 
tion does  not  exist,  and  the  equations  of  condition  may  depend  ex- 
plicitly on  the  time.  Thus  Lagrange's  principle  is  far  more  general 
than  Jacobi's. 

Of  late  years,  the  occurrence  of  differential  and  non-integrable 
equations  among  the  equations  of  condition  of  a  problem  has  as- 
sumed great  importance.  This  happens  in  certain  cases  of  rolling 
motion,  and  systems  with  such  equations  of  condition  were  called 
by  Hertz  non-holonomous.  The  question  arises  as  to  whether  the 
principle  of  least  action  and  Hamilton's  principle  can  be  so  formu- 
lated as  to  apply  to  non-holonomous  systems.  We  shall  see  that 
Otto  Holder  first  succeeded  in  formulating  extended  forms  of  both 
principles  which  were  completely  equivalent  to  d'Alembert's  prin- 
ciple. There  were,  of  course,  several  points '  not  dealt  with  by 
Holder  on  which  it  was  essential  to  be  quite  clear.  Thus,  the  pro- 
cess of  "variation"  used  by  Holder  was  not  always  the  one  to  which 
we  are  accustomed  in  the  calculus  of  variations,  and  the  transforma- 
tion of  the  principles  from  rectangular  coordinates — which  alone 
were  used  by  Holder — to  more  general  coordinates  gives  rise  to 
interesting  questions.  However,  it  seems  to  me  that  we  have  now- 
reached  a  certain  degree  of  finality  in  all  these  subjects,  and  we  will 
now  present  the  researches  whose  object  was  to  extend  the  prin- 
ciples, in  their  proper  order,  and,  where  necessary,  comment  on 
them. 


VII. 

The  question  as  to  the  extent  of  the  variational  principles  be- 
gins with  the  publication,  in  1894,  of  Heinrich  Hertz's  posthumous 
Prinzipien  der  Mechanik.*0  "The  application  of  Hamilton's  prin- 

80  Gesammelte  Werke  von  Heinrich  Hertz,  Vol.  Ill,  Die  Prinzipien  der 
Mechanik  in  neuem  Zusammenhange  dargestellt  (edited  by  Ph.  Lenard,  with 
a  preface  by  H.  von  Helmholtz),  Leipsic,  1894;  English  translation  by  D.  E. 
Jones  and  J.  T.  Walley  under  the  title  The  Principles  of  Mechanics,  London, 
1899- 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

ciple,"  said  Hertz^1  "to  a  material  system  does  not  exclude  fixed 
connections  between  the  coordinates  chosen,  but  it  requires  that  these 
connections  can  be  exposed  mathematically  by  means  of  finite  equa- 
tions between  the  coordinates ;  it  does  not  permit  of  such  connections 
as  can  be  expressed  only  by  differential  equations.  But  nature  itself 
appears  not  simply  to  exclude  connections  of  the  latter  kind;  for 
they  occur  if,  for  example,  three-dimensional  bodies  roll  upon  one 
another  without  slipping." 

Hertzs*  called  a  material  system  holonomous  if  between  possible 
positions  all  thinkable  continuous  passages  are  also  possible.  The 
name  was  chosen  to  indicate  that  such  a  system  is  subject  to  integral 
(oAos)  laws  (voVos),  while  material  systems  in  general  are  subject 
only  to  differential  laws.  If  the  differential  equations  of  condition 
of  a  material  system  can  all  be  integrated,  the  coordinates  of  every 
possible  position  must  satisfy  the  finite  equations.  The  differences 
between  the  coordinates  of  two  neighboring  positions  therefore 
satisfy  an  equal  number  of  homogeneous  linear  differential  equa- 
tions, and,  since  these  latter  cannot  contradict  the  given  differential 
equations  (in  equal  number)  of  the  system,  they  satisfy  the  latter 
too.  Thus  the  displacement  between  any  two  possible  positions 
is  a  possible  displacement,  and  thus  the  system  is  holonomous.  In- 
versely, if  the  system  is  holonomous,  its  differential  equations  of 
condition  allow  an  equal  number  of  finite  or  integral  equations  be- 
tween the  coordinates  themselves. 

VIII. 

Here  we  may  digress  to  remark  that  the  fact  that  cases  of 
rolling  motion  give  rise  to  equations  of  condition  which  are  not 
integrable  was  observed  by  Routh,  Ferrers  (1873),  and  C.  Neu- 
mann (1888). 53  The  usual  form  of  Lagrange's  equations  then  fails. 
Of  the  extensions,  what  I  have  called,  in  the  paper  just  quoted, 
"Routh's  form"  is  the  most  important  form  for  our  present  pur- 
poses. It  involves  Lagrange's  multipliers,  and  is  the  only  form  of 
equation  valid  for  non-holonomous  systems  which  can  be  got  di- 
rectly by  development  of  one  of  the  integral  variational  principles. 
In  deducing  equations  of  motion  from,  say,  Hamilton's  principle, 

61  Werke,  Vol.  Ill,  pp.  22-25 ;  Principles,  pp.  19-21. 

M  Werke,  Vol.  Ill,  articles  123,  132,  and  133  (pp.  91,  95,  and  96)  ^Prin- 
ciples, pp.  80,  84-85. 

"*  Cf.  the  note  on  p.  63  of  my  paper  "On  the  General  Equations  of  Mechan- 
ics," Quart.  Journ.  of  Math.,  1904,  pp.  61-79.  Cf.  the  bibliography  in  P.  Ap- 
pell's  little  book  on  Les  mouvements  de  roulement  en  dynamique,  Paris,  1899. 


298  THE  MONIST. 

we  so  to  speak  divide  the  material  system  into  a  holonomous  and 
a  non-holonomous  part.  Suppose  there  are  3n  rectangular  -co- 
ordinates of  the  system,  k  finite  equations  of  condition  between 
these  coordinates  and  the  time,  and  /  non-integrable  equations  of 
condition.  We  form  our  integral  for  a  system  with  3n-k  degrees 
of  freedom  and  then  eliminate  the  /  superfluous  coordinates  by  La- 
grange's  method. 

IX. 

An  important  paper  on  the  differential  equations  of  mechanics 
was  written  by  A.  VossS4  in  1884  and  published  in  1885.  In  this 
paper,  the  equations  of  condition  were  used  in  their  differential 
form,  and  were  not  assumed  to  be  integrable,  although  the  problems 
of  rolling  motion  which  caused  such  equations  to  be  considered  were 
not  mentioned.  The  part  which  especially  concerns  us  here  is  where 
Voss  uses  Hamilton's  principle  for  the  introduction  of  more  general 
coordinates.  He  saysss  that,  with  non-integrable  equations  of  condi- 
tion, "the  transformation  can  no  longer  be  reduced  to  a  problem 
of  variations  properly  so  called,  but  the  property  of  the  system  of 
differential  equations  of  condition  of  being  a  complete  one  forms 
the  necessary  and  sufficient  condition  for  this." 

x. 

Hertz  decided  that  his  own  fundamental  law56  holds  both  for 
holonomous  and  non-holonomous  systems,  and  that  from  this  law 
result  the  principle  of  least  actions?  and  Hamilton's  principles8  only 
under  a  limitation  to  holonomous  systems.  But  this  contradicts  the 
general  conviction^  that  Hamilton's  principle  is  merely  a  trans- 
formation of  d'Alembert's  principle,  and  that  the  latter  holds  gen- 
erally, and  is  equivalent  to  Hertz's  law.60  Thus  arose  the  questions 
as  to  whether  the  usual  derivation  of  Hamilton's  principle  from  that 
of  d'Alembert  requires  any  limiting  supposition.  This  question  was 
the  origin  of  the  researches  of  Otho  Holder.61  The  very  kernel  of 

""Ueber  die  Differentialgleichungen  der  Mechanik,"  Math.  Ann..  Vol. 
XXV,  1885,  pp.  258-286. 

"Ibid.,  pp.  263-264. 

"  Werke,  Vol.  Ill,  art.  309,  p.  162 ;  Principles,  p.  144. 

"Werke,  Vol.  Ill,  arts.  347-356,  pp.  174-176;  Principles,  pp.  155-157. 

**  Werke,  Vol.  Ill,  arts.  358-362,  p.  177;  Principles,  pp.  158-159. 

69  See,  for  example,  Mach,  Mechanik,  pp.  413-414 ;  Mechanics,  p.  381. 

*  Werke,  Vol.  Ill,  art.  394,  p.  186;  Principles,  p.  166. 

""Ueber  die  Principien  von  Hamilton  und  Maupertuis,"  Nachr.  von  der 
konigl  Ges.  der  Wiss.  zu  Gottingen,  Math.  phys.  Klasse,  1896,  pp.  122-157. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  2QQ 

Holder's  work  is  his  conception  of  the  "variation  of  the  motion  of 
a  system;"  this  it  was  which  allowed  him  to  give  such  a  wide  ex- 
tension to  the  principles  of  least  action  and  of  Hamilton,  so  that  the 
reply  to  the  above  question  is:  If  d'Alembert's  principle  holds  gen- 
erally, so  also  must  that  of  Hamilton,  in  its  completest  form ;  but 
if  we  choose  Hertz's  view  that  the  varied  path  be  a  possible  one, 
we  get  the  limitation  denoted  by  him.  Holder's  conception  of  a 
varied  motion  is,  then,  paradoxical  in  so  far  that  this  "motion"  need 
not  be  a  possible  one, — need  not  satisfy  the  equations  of  condition. 
It  is,  in  Holder's  own  words,  only  a  mathematical  auxiliary  con- 
ception. 

With  Hertz,  Holder  understood  by  "the  position  of  a  system" 
the  totality  of  the  positions  of  the  material  points  of  the  system; 
the  motion  consists  in  a  continuous  sequence  of  positions  of  the 
system,  which  are  passed  through  in  a  definite  way  with  the  time. 
To  vary  this  original  motion,  we  first  give  every  system-position 
a  small  displacement,  so  that  a  new  continuous  sequence  of  positions 
arises.  If  the  original  sequence  gives  one  position  twice,  we  have 
two  positions  covering  one  another  which  can  naturally  be  displaced 
in  different  manners.  The  starting  position  A  and  the  final  position 
B  are  to  be  fixed,  and  we  refer  each  position  on  the  varied  path  to 
one  on  the  actual  path.  This  correspondence  is  necessary  in  order 
that  we  may  put  the  variation  of  an  integral  taken  along  the  original 
path  equal  to  the  integral  of  the  varied  elements.  We  coordinate 
the  identical  initial  positions  to  one  another,  and  similarly  with  the 
two  final  positions. 

If  we  imagine  both  the  actual62  and  the  fictitious  motion  to  begin 
simultaneously  at  A,  then  the  systems  need  not  arrive  at  B  simul- 
taneously. In  this  case  the  corresponding  positions  on  the  two  paths 
cannot  all  be  passed  simultaneously,  and  if  the  passage  from  an 
actual  position  to  the  corresponding  position  on  the  fictitious  path 
be  denoted  by  8,  so  that,  if  the  position  P  is  actually  reached  at  the 
time  t,  the  corresponding  position  P  +  8P  is  reached  at  the  time 
t  +  Bt  and  8(dt)  =  d(8t). 

Now,  in  the  most  general  manner  of  variation  of  the  motion, 
we  can  still  choose  the  velocity  at  each  point  of  the  varied  path. 
This  must  be  infinitely  little  different  from  the  velocity  at  the  cor- 
responding position  of  the  actual  path,  but  is  otherwise  arbitrary. 

Holder  then  found  the  expression  for  8T  in  rectangular  coordi- 

MThus  it  is  assumed  that  the  mechanical  problem  has  one  solution  and 
one  only. 


3OO  THE  MONIST. 

nates,  t  and  dt  being  affected  by  the  8-process,  integrated  the  identity 
for  8T  from  t0  to  f±  (the  times  when  the  system,  in  the  actual  motion, 
is  at  A  and  B  respectively),  and  integrated  by  parts.  Thus,  two 
parts  are  obtained:  one  integrated,  which  vanishes,  since  the  varia- 
tions of  the  coordinates  at  A  and  B  vanish ;  and  the  other  uninte- 
grated,  and  we  see  by  d'Alembert's  principle,  that  the  integrand 
of  the  last  integral  can  be  put  equal  to  8U  where,  as  before,  "8U" 
only  denotes  the  variation  of  a  force  function  U  in  special  cases — 
provided  that  the  variations  of  the  coordinates  represent  virtual 
displacements  of  the  system.6^  Thus  Holder  obtained  the  result 
that,  where  the  8-process  is  a  process  of  giving  every  position  P 
between  A  and  B  a  virtual  displacement  to  P+8P,  and  the  aggregate 
of  positions  P+8P  is  conceived  as  a  fictitious  path,  then  the  equation 

/{2T.<*8f  +  (8T  +  8U)df)  =0,  (4) 

where  the  integral  is  to  be  taken  between  the  limits  t0  and  tlt  is 
equivalent  to  d'Alembert's  principle. 

We  cannot  too  strongly  emphasize  the  nature  of  this  varied  path 
of  the  system.  It  is  not  necessarily  a  path  that  the  system,  however 
constrained,  could  take ;  that  is  to  say,  the  connections  of  the  system 
might  have  to  be  distorted  from  point  to  point.  The  displacement 
8P  must  be  virtual  at  the  instant  t,  but  the  position  P  +  8P  is 
"reached"  by  the  system,  supposed  to  "move"  on  a  fictitious  path 
in  a  perhaps  impossible  way,  at  the,  in  general  different,  time 
t  +  8t.  In  fact,  the  fictitious  path  is  only  a  possible  one,  of  course 
under  new  constraints,  if  the  equations  of  the  condition  are  inde- 
pendent of  the  time,  and  the  system  is  holonomous. 

This  fictitious  motion  is  a  useful  conception  because  it  enables 
us  to  see  exactly  why  Hertz,  for  example,  rather  naturally  limited 
the  scope  of  the  principle  of  least  action  and  Hamilton's  principle  to 
holonomous  systems ;  and  also  it  allows  us  to  formulate  these  prin- 
ciples in  a  perfectly  general  manner.  That  the  conception  of  a 
"variation"  is  not  that  of  the  calculus  of  variations  did  not  escape 
Holder.  "At  the  first  glance,"  he  wrote,6*  "the  conception  is  perhaps 
peculiar;  and  it  has  been  already  said  to  me  that  I  have  no  problem 
of  variation  properly  so  called.  But  that  does  not  concern  me.  I 
am  only  concerned  with  giving  a  clear  signification  to  the  variations 
of  the  coordinates  and  the  time  which  at  the  same  time  is  such  that 

"That  is  to  say,  displacements  consistent  with  the  equations  of  condition 
and  possible,  at  the  instant  considered.  Cf.,  for  example,  Mach,  Mechanik,  p. 
58 ;  Mechanics,  pp.  49,  56. 

84  In  a  letter  to  me  of  Jan.  15,  1904;  cf.  Quart.  Journ.  of  Math.,  1904,  p.  75, 
last  note. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  30! 

the  principles  hold  as  generally  as  is  possible."  In  conformity  with 
this,  Holder  spoke  of  an  "altered"  (abgednderte)  instead  of  a 
"varied"  motion. 

In  the  above  general  principle,  we  can,  without  detracting 
from  the  equivalence  to  d'Alembert's  principle,  specialize  the  varia- 
tions. Two  ways  at  once  suggest  themselves: 

(1)  We  may  determine  that  corresponding  positions  are  to  be 
passed  at  the  same  instant,  so  that  8t  =  0,  then  (4)  becomes  a  gen- 
eralized Hamilton's  principle; 

(2)  We  may  determine  the  velocity  at  each  point  of  the  varied 
path  by  fixing  that  8T  =  8U,  the  variation  of  the  time  being,  of 
course,  not  zero  ;  that  is  to  say,  using  a  more  restricted  phraseology 
for  this  wider  case,  the  total  energy  is  constant  in  a  variation  ;  then 
(4)  gives  the  principle  of  least  action  in  its  most  extended  form. 

XI. 

There  is  one  rather  important  point  upon  which  Holder  only 
touched  very  briefly.  I  mean  the  introduction  of  other  more  general 
coordinates  into  the  development  of  equations  of  motion  from  the 
above  principles.  Voss  attempted  to  do  this  in  1900,  but,  as  I  have 
shown,  6s  he  used  a  method  previously  used  by  Routh  and  Rethy, 
which  preserved  the  strictly  variational  character  of  the  8-process 
used  even  when  the  equations  of  condition  depend  explicitly  on  the 
time.  Thus  Voss  unintentionally  abandoned  Holder's  8-process. 
The  application  of  Holder's  process  to  the  formulation  of  the  prin- 
ciples in  general  coordinates  was  first  carried  out  by  myself  in  the 
above  cited  paper  of  1904,  and  more  clearly  in  a  paper  of  1908.66 
Mathematically  speaking,  this  formulation  is  not  quite  so  simple 
as  some  might  suppose  ;  but  here  we  are  only  concerned  with  the 
advantages  of  Holder's  8-process  over  the  strictly  variational  process 
in  the  formulation  of  the  principle  of  least  action  and  Hamilton's 
principle.  The  abandonment  of  the  strict  conception  of  a  variation 
may  appear  to  be  a  disadvantage.  But  surely  this  is  compensated 
by  greater  simplicity  ;  while,  in  my  case,  when  we  come  to  deal  with 
non-holonomous  systems  we  must  abandon  this  strict  conception, 
as  was  pointed  out  —  we  have  seen  above  —  by  Voss  in  1884  and  by 
others  later  in  somewhat  different  forms.  6?  Further,  unless  the 


"Math.  Ann.,  Vol.  LXV,  1908,  pp.  517-525. 
"Math.  Ann.,  Vol.  LXV,  1908,  pp.  525-527. 


67  C.  Neumann  (1888),  Hertz  (1894),  Holder  (1896),  and  Appell  (1898); 
see  also  Boltzmann,  Vorlesungen  iiber  die  Prinzipe  der  Mechanik,  Teil  II, 
Leipsic,  1904,  pp.  30-34. 


3O2  THE  MONIST. 

equations  of  condition  do  not  contain  the  time  explicitly,  the  form 
of  Rethy  and  Voss  requires  a  condition  holding  for  St  at  the  limits 
of  integration,  whereas  in  Holder's  generalized  principle  of  least 
action  no  such  condition  is  required. 

XII. 

As  we  have  said  at  the  beginning,  Mach  has  stated,  with  ref- 
erence to  the  principles  of  least  action  and  Hamilton,  that  other 
such  principles  are  possible.  In  this  connection  there  are  two  in- 
vestigations to  which  we  must  refer.  The  first  was  by  Voss68  in 
1901,  and  was  inspired  by  Holder's  work.  Voss  remarked  that  if 
not  only  the  coordinates,  but  also  the  time  is  varied  in  the  most 
general  manner,  8t  can  always  be  determined  subsequently  so  that 
if  we  put  the  variation  of  the  integral  of  any  function  of  the  co- 
ordinates and  velocities  equal  to  zero,  we  get  the  equation  of  mo- 
tion. The  second  was  an  attempt  by  myself6^  to  solve  the  problem 
suggested  by  Mach,  by  determining  all  the  possible  integral  varia- 
tional  principles.  For  this  purpose  I  inquired  what  was  the  most 
general  form  of  the  integrand  in  order  that  the  principle  obtained 
hence  should  be  equivalent  to  Routh's  extension  of  Lagrange's 
equations.  The  result  was  to  find  that  Holder's  principle  (4)  was 
the  most  general  of  its  kind,  and,  as  Holder  had  remarked,  his 
principle  may  be  specialized  into  Hamilton's  principle  or  the  prin- 
ciple of  least  action.  These  two  principles  are,  in  fact,  two  special 
cases  out  of  the  manifold  of  the  principles  equivalent  to  d'Alem- 
bert's  principle  and  derivable  from  (4)  by  determining  St  generally 
in  all  possible  ways. 

But  there  is  another  aspect  of  the  matter.  We  have  taken  La- 
grange's  equations,  or  rather  Routh's  extension  of  them,  as  funda- 
mental. But  there  are  other  forms  of  the  equations  of  mechanics 
involving  other  quantities  than  Lagrange's  T  and  U,  and  which 
sometimes  present  advantages  over  Lagrange's.?0  From  these  other 
equations  we  can  derive?1  other  variational  principles  not  contained 
in  Holder's  form  (4),  but  since  the  functions  in  the  integrand  now 
involve  differential  coefficients  with  respect  to  t  of  the  second 

88  "Bemerkungen  iiber  die  Prinzipien  der  Mechanik,"  Sitzber.  der  math.- 
phys.  Klasse  der  k.  Bayer.  Akad.  der  Wiss.  zu  Munchen,  Vol.  XXXI,  1901,  pp. 
167-182,  especially  pp.  171-175;  Encykl  der  math.  Wiss.,  IV,  i,  1901,  p.  94. 

M  Quart.  Journ.  of  Math.,  1904,  pp.  76-78. 

70  Cf.  my  paper  on  "Alternative  Forms  of  the  Equations  of  Mechanics/' 
in  the  Quart.  Journ.  of  Math.,  1905,  pp.  284-296. 

n  Cf.  Ibid.,  pp.  290-295. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  303 

order,  we  must  determine  the  varied  path  so  that  not  only  the 
variations  Sq  but  also  the  differentials  d8q  of  these  variations  vanish 
at  the  limits  of  integration.  Analogous  conditions  as  to  the  paths 
arise,  if  the  integrand  contains  higher  differential  coefficients  than 
the  second. 

XIII. 

A  curious  result,72  by  the  way,  is  that  if  we  vary  the  integral 
of  action  f2T.dt,  so  that  &tr  means,  as  with  Holder,  a  virtual  dis- 
placement of  x,  and  vary  t,  we  get  exactly  the  same  result  as  if  we 
had  not  varied  t  either  in  T  or  in  dt:  the  extra  terms  we  get  from 
varying  t  happen  to  cancel  one  another.  Hence  the  faulty  deriva- 
tion, which  we  sometimes  see,  of  Hamilton's  principle  from  the 
principle  of  least  action  leads  to  correct  results.  This  derivation 
is  :  Since  8T  =  8U,  we  have 


It  should  be  noticed  that  the  extra  terms  above  referred  to  cancel 
even  if  the  equations  of  condition  contain  the  time  explicitly.  Fur- 
ther, we  have  seen  that  the  identification  maintained  by  Helmholtz 
and  Rethy  of  Hamilton's  principle  with  the  principle  of  least  action 
depended  on  the  equations  of  condition  not  containing  the  time  ex- 
plicitly ;  and  that  the  other  identifications  were  based  on  misunder- 
standings. Finally,  we  have  seen  how  in  Holder's  other  work,  the 
true  relation  of  the  principles  became  clear,  and  how,  at  the  same 
time,  the  principle  became  generalized. 

XIV. 

This  sketch  of  the  development  and  gradual  generalization  of 
a  small  part  of  the  theory  of  mechanics  gives  us  food  for  meditation. 
It  seems  to  be  necessary,  in  order  that  it  may  be  possible  to  state  the 
principles  in  question  quite  generally,  to  make  use  of  a  paradoxical 
conception  —  the  conception  of  a  generalized,  fictitious  "motion."  It 
would  be  easy  to  say  that  the  principles  are,  by  the  laws  of  logic, 
valid  only  under  certain  conditions  ;  hence  the  paradox  when  we 
attempt  to  widen  those  conditions.  But  the  paradox  is  not  logical  ; 
it  is  merely  verbal.  We  speak  of  a  fictitious  "path"  and  "motion" 
merely  for  the  sake  of  picturesqueness  :  a  mathematician  no  more 
means  to  imply  the  existence,  in  a  mystical  region  of  thought,  of  an 
impossible  and  fictitious  path  or  motion,  than  he  means  to  imply 
anything  more  than  striking  analogies  of  expression  when  he  speaks, 

n  Quart.  Journ.  of  Math.,  1904,  pp.  78-79. 


304  THE  MONIST. 

in  analytical  geometry,  of  "imaginary  intersections"  or  "circular 
points  at  infinity."  No  philosopher  wishes  to  confute  a  mathemati- 
cian because,  in  his  technical  language,  the  mathematician  may 
assert  that  some  "real"  numbers  are  not  "rational." 

PHILIP  E.  B.  JOURDAIN. 
THE  LODGE,  GIRTON,  CAMBRIDGE,  ENGLAND. 


NOTES  ON  THE  CONSTRUCTION  OF  MAGIC  SQUARES 

OF  ORDERS  IN  WHICH  H  IS  OF  THE  GENERAL  FORM  4/M-2. 

It  is  well  known  that  magic  squares  of  the  above  orders,  i.  e., 
62, 102, 142, 182,  etc.,  cannot  be  made  perfectly  pandiagonal  and  ornate 
with  the  natural  series  of  numbers. 

Dr.  C.  Planck  has  however  pointed  out  that  this  disability  is 
purely  arithmetical,  seeing  that  these  magics  can  be  readily  con- 
structed as  perfect  and  ornate  as  any  others  with  a  properly  selected 
series  of  numbers. 

In  all  of  these  squares  n  is  of  the  general  form  4p  +  2,  but  they 
can  be  divided  into  two  classes : 

Class    I.  Where  n  is  of  the  form  8/>  -  2,  as  62,  142,  222  etc. 

Class  II.  Where  n  is  of  the  form  Sp  +  2,  as  102,  182,  262  etc. 

The  series  for  all  magics  of  Class  I  may  be  derived  by  making 
a  square  of  the  natural  series  1  to  (w+1)2  and  discarding  the  numbers 
in  the  middle  row  and  column. 

Thus,  for  a  62  magic  the  series  will  be: 

1     2    3   -   -   5     6    7 
8    9    10  --  12  13  14 
15  16  17  -  -  19  20  21 

29  30  31  —  33  34  35 
36  37  38  --  40  41  42 
43  44  45  —  47  48  49 

The  series  for  all  magics  of  Class  II  may  be  made  by  writing 
a  square  of  the  natural  numbers  1  to  (n+3)2  and  discarding  the 
numbers  in  the  three  middle  rows  and  columns.  The  series  for  a 
102  magic,  for  example,  will  be: 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  305 

1      2      3      4      5       ...      9     10    11  12  13 

14     15     16     17     18      ...      22    23    24  25  26 

27    28    29    30    31      ...      35     36    37  38  39 

40    41     42    43    44      ...      48    49    50  51  52 

53    54    55    56    57  61    62    63  64  65 


105  106  107  108  109  ...  113  114  115  116  117 

118  119  120  121  122  ...  126  127  128  129  130 

131  132  133  134  135  ...  139  140  141  142  143 

144  145  146  147  148  ...  152  153  154  155  156 

157  158  159  160  161  ...  165  166  167  168  169 

By  using  series  as  above  described,  pandiagonal  magics  with 
double-ply  properties,  or  associated  magics  may  be  readily  made 
either  by  the  La  Hireian  method  with  magic  rectangles,  or  by  the 
path  method  as  developed  by  Dr.  C.  Planck. 

Referring  now  to  the  La  Hireian  method  and  using  the  6* 
magic  as  a  first  example,  the  rectangles  required  for  making  the 
two  auxiliary  squares  will  necessarily  be  2x3,  and  the  numbers  used 
therein  will  be  those  commonly  employed  for  squares  of  the  seventh 
order,  i.  e.,  (6+1  )2,  with  the  middle  numbers  omitted  thus: 
123     —     567 
0      7      14  28    35    42 

It  may  be  shown  that  a  magic  rectangle  having  an  odd  number 
of  cells  in  one  side,  and  an  even  number  of  cells  in  the  other  side 
is  impossible  with  consecutive  numbers,  but  with  a  series  made  as 
above  it  can  be  constructed  without  any  difficulty,  as  shown  in 
Figs.  1  and  2. 

Two  auxiliary  squares  may  now  be  made  by  filling  them  with 
their  respective  rectangles.  If  this  is  done  without  forethought, 
a  plain  pandiagonal  magic  of  the  sixth  order  may  result,  but  if 
attention  is  given  to  ornate  qualities  in  the  two  auxiliaries,  these 
features  will  naturally  be  carried  into  the  final  square.  For  example, 


306 


THE  MONIST. 


by  the  arrangement  of  rectangles  shown  in  Figs.  3  and  4  both  auxil- 
iaries are  made  magic  in  their  six  rows,  six  columns  and  twelve 


Fig.  2. 


0 

42 

0 

42 

0 

** 

3S 

7 

Jf 

7 

3S 

7 

zs 

'4- 

Zf 

'4 

z$ 

/4 

0 

42 

O 

4-2 

o 

4-2 

3f 

7 

3$ 

7 

3S 

7 

2<? 

'4 

2S 

/* 

2<? 

'4 

Fig.  4. 


7 

z 

3 

3 

Z 

7 

/ 

6 

<r 

S 

6 

/ 

7 

z 

3 

3 

z 

7 

/ 

6 

cT 

& 

6 

/ 

7 

Z 

3 

3 

z 

7 

/ 

6 

& 

<? 

6 

/ 

Fig.  6. 


7 

z 

6 

7 

z 

3 

/ 

6 

<? 

/ 

6 

s 

7 

Z 

3 

7 

z 

3 

/ 

6 

f 

/ 

6 

& 

7 

2 

J 

7 

2 

<3 

/ 

6 

S 

/ 

6 

& 

Fig.  3- 


7 

44 

3 

49 

Z 

4$ 

s^~~\ 

(36 

\^  J 

/3 

40 

/"~"\ 

*  } 

\^  ^/ 

4/ 

/Z 

3S 

/6 

3/ 

Z/ 

30 

'7 

/~^ 
\^S 

43 

& 

s^~\ 
%£ 

6 

*7 

42 

3 

3# 

/4 

*7 

/o 

'f  ^\ 
& 

ZO 

33 

r  A 
<*) 

34 

/& 

Fig.  5- 


o 

42 

0 

^2 

O 

42 

33T 

7 

35 

7 

35 

7 

ZS 

/4 

zs 

'4 

ZS 

/^ 

2S 

'*- 

2# 

'& 

Z8 

/^ 

3S 

7 

3S 

7 

3S 

7 

O 

/+2 

O 

42 

0 

4.Z 

Fig.  7- 


diagonals,  and  they  are  also  4-ply  and  9-ply.    Their  .complementary 
couplets  are  also  harmoniously  connected   throughout  in  steps  of 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 


307 


3,  3.  These  ornate  features  are  therefore  transmitted  into  the  fin- 
ished 62  magic  shown  in  Fig.  5.  If  it  is  desired  to  make  this  square 
associated,  that  is  with  its  complementary  couplets  evenly  balanced 
around  its  center,  it  is  only  necessary  to  introduce  the  feature  of 
association  into  the  two  auxiliary  squares  by  a  rearrangement  of 
their  magic  rectangles  as  shown  in  Figs.  6,  7  and  8,  the  last  figure 
being  a  pandiagonal  associated  magic. 


36 


42 


/J 


/6 


20 


'7 


/o 


4? 


4' 


34 


8 


Z/ 


Fig.  8. 

The  next  larger  square  of  Class  I  is  142,  and  it  can  be  made 
with  the  natural  series  1  to  (14-fl)2  arranged  in  a  square,  discard- 
ing, as  before,  all  the  numbers  in  the  central  row  and  column. 

The  rectangles  for  this  square  will  necessarily  be  2x7  and  the 
numbers  written  therein  will  be  those  ordinarily  used  for  a  square 
of  the  fifteenth  order,  (14+1)2,  with  the  middle  numbers  omitted, 
thus: 


1234567      — 
0     15    30    45    60    75    90    — 


9  10  11  12  13  14  15 
120  135  150  165  180  195  210 


AT 

Z 

6 

/Z 

// 

6 

7 

z/o 

/s 

30 

/6e5T 

/tt 

/s- 

90 

/ 

/4 

/3 

4 

JT 

/o 

& 

o 

/&s 

/so 

4& 

60 

/3S 

/£0 

Fig.   9- 


Fig.    10. 


Simple  forms  of  magic  rectangles  for  the  auxiliaries  are  shown 
in  Figs.  9  and  10,  but  many  other  arrangements  of  the  couplets  will 
work  equally  well. 

The  smallest  magic  of  Class  II  is  102,  the  series  for  which  is 
given  below.  The  rectangles  used  for  filling  the  two  auxiliaries  of 
this  square  are  2x5,  and  they  can  be  made  with  the  numbers  which 


308 


THE  MONIST. 


would  be  commonly  used  for  a  square  of  the  thirteenth  order  (10+3)a 
omitting  the  three  middle  numbers  in  each  row  thus : 

1      2      3      4      5       ...       9     10    11     12     13 
0     13    26    39    52      ...     104  117  130  143  156 
Figs.  11  and  12  show  these  two  rectangles  with  a  simple  ar- 
rangement of  the  numbers.  The  two  auxiliaries  and  the  finished  102 


/J 

2 

// 

<£ 

cT 

/ 

/2 

3 

/o 

3 

/S6 

/3 

/30 

39 

<?£ 

O 

/4$ 

26 

"7 

/04 

Fig.  ii. 


Fig.  12. 


magic  are  given  in  Figs.  13,  14  and  15.  Fig.  15  is  magic  in  its 
ten  rows,  ten  columns  and  twenty  diagonals.  It  is  also  4-ply  and 
25-ply.  Like  the  62  magic,  this  square  can  also  be  associated  by 
changing  the  disposition  of  the  magic  rectangles  in  the  auxiliaries. 


/J 


/3 


/2 


/2 


/  2 


/2 


/2 


/o 


/o 


/o 


/o 


S 


S 


S 


/J 


/2 


/  2 


Z 


/  2 


/Z 


/O 


/O 


/o 


/o 


/o 


Fig.  13. 

The  above  examples  will  suffice  to  explain  the  general  con- 
struction of  these  squares  by  the  La  Hireian  method  with  magic 
rectangles.  It  may  however  be  stated  that  although  the  series  pre- 
viously described  for  use  in  building  these  squares  include  the  lower 
numerical  values,  there  are  other  series  of  higher  numbers  which 
will  produce  equivalent  magic  results. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 


309 


0 


O 


0 


/3 


/J 


26 


/SO 


26 


/SO 


26 


/SO 


"7 


"7 


"7 


"7 


"7 


SZ 


o 


0 


0 


O 


/s6 


o 


/3 


/3 


'3 


26 


26 


/SO 


26 


/so 


26 


/SO 


"7 


"7 


" 


7 


39 


" 


7 


sz 


JZ 


52 


SZ 


soy 


Fig.  14. 


/6o 


/6s 


/<$ 


22 


39 


3/ 


2$ 


30 


S3S 


//S 


/ZO 


40 


/za 


*? 


" 


7 


//s 


s6 


63 


/s 


7 


/z 


/se 


/o 


/s 


7 


Z6 


24 


27 


Z9 


3* 


S33 


36 


S39 


/3O 


S22 


sz 


sv 


6z 


S3 


Fig.  15. 


6/ 


3io 


THE  MONIST. 


The  following  table  illustrates  another  rule  covering  the  selec- 
tion of  numbers  for  all  magic  squares  of  these  orders. 


ORDER 
OF 
SQUARE 

NATURAL  SERIES 

DISCARDING   NUMBERS   IN 

6th 

1  to  (  6+1)2 

the  middle  row  and  column. 

10th 

1  to  (  10+3)  2 

the  3  middle  rows  and  columns. 

14th 

1  to(14+5)2 

the  5  middle  rows  and  columns. 

18th 

1  to(18+7)2 

the  7  middle  rows  and  columns. 

22nd 

1  to  (22+9)  2 

the  9  middle  rows  and  columns. 

26th 

1  to  (26+1  1)2 

the  11  middle  rows  and  columns. 

and  so  forth. 

numbers  of  the  natural  series  ( 


These  figures  show  that  this  rule  is  equivalent  to  taking  the 

V  n-4 

)    and  omitting  the  central     ^ 

rows  and  columns.  In  comparing  the  above  with  the  rules  pre- 
viously given,  for  which  we  are  indebted  to  Dr.  C.  Planck,  it  will 
be  seen  that  in  cases  of  magics  larger  than  102  it  involves  the  use  of 
unnecessarily  large  numbers. 

The  numerical  values  of  the  ply  properties  of  these  squares 
are  naturally  governed  by  the  dimensions  of  the  magic  rectangles 
used  in  their  construction.  Thus  the  rectangle  of  the  62  magic 
(Fig.  5)  is  2x3,  and  this  square  is  22-ply  and  32-ply.  The  rectangle 
of  the  102  magic  being  2x5,  the  square  may  be  made  22-ply  and 
52-ply,  and  so  forth. 

The  formation  of  these  squares  by  the  Path  method  which  has 
been  so  ably  developed  by  Dr.  C.  Planck,1  may  now  be  considered. 
The  first  step  is  to  rearrange  the  numbers  of  the  given  series  in 
such  a  cyclic  order  or  sequence,  that  each  number  being  written  con- 
secutively into  the  square  by  a  well  defined  rule  or  path,  the  re- 
sulting magic  will  be  identical  with  that  made  by  the  La  Hireian 
method,  or  equivalent  thereto  in  magic  qualities.  Starting,  as  before, 
with  the  62  magic,  the  proper  sequence  of  the  first  six  numbers  is 
found  in  what  may  be  termed  the  "continuous  diagonal"  of  its  magic 
rectangle.  Referring  to  Fig.  1,  this  sequence  is  seen  to  be  1;  2,  5, 
7,  6,  3,  but  it  is  obvious  that  there  may  be  as  many  different  se- 
quences as  there  are  variations  in  the  magic  rectangles. 

The  complete  series  given  on  page  304  must  now  be  rearranged 

1  "The  Theory  of  Path  Nasiks,"  by  C  Planck,  M.A.,  M.R.C.S.,  published 
by  A.  T.  Lawrence,  Rugby,  England. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 


in  its  lines  and  columns  in  accordance  with  the  numerical  sequence 
of  the  first  six  numbers  as  above  indicated.  To  make  this  arrange- 
ment quite  clear,  the  series  given  on  p.  304  is  reproduced  in  Fig.  16, 
the  numbers  written  in  circles  outside  the  square  showing  the  numer- 
ical order  of  lines  and  columns  under  rearrangement.  Fig.  17  shows 
the  complete  series  in  new  cyclic  order,  and  to  construct  a  square 
directly  therefrom,  it  is  only  necessary  to  write  these  numbers  con- 
secutively along  the  proper  paths.  Since  the  square  will  be  pandiag- 
onal  it  may  be  commenced  anywhere,  so  in  the  present  example  we 
will  place  1  in  the  fourth  cell  from  the  top  in  the  first  column,  and 
will  use  the  paths  followed  in  Fig.  5  so  as  to  reproduce  that  square. 


The  paths  may  be  written   I  3,  2 

(4,3 


and  since  we  can  always  write 


/6 


JO 


/o 


'7 


6 


zo 


4* 


7 


Z9 


36 


30 


/6 


jr 


J3 


7 


Z/ 


6 


/O 


4* 


Fig.  16. 
-(n-a)  instead  of  a,  we  may  write  this 


Fig.i;. 
This  only  means 


3,2 
-2,3 

that  the  numbers  in  the  first  column  of  Fig.  17  (which  may  be 
termed  the  leading  numbers)  are  to  be  placed  in  order  along  the 
path  (3,  2),  as  in  the  numbers  enclosed  in  circles  in  Fig.  5; 'and 
then  starting  from  each  cell  thus  occupied,  the  remaining  five  num- 
bers in  each  of  the  six  rows  of  Fig.  17  are  to  be  written  along  the 
path  (-2,  3).  It  will  be  seen  that  this  is  equivalent  to  writing  the 
successive  rows  of  Fig.  17  intact  along  the  path  (-2,  3),  or  (3,  -2) 
and  using  a  "break-step"  (1,  -1),  as  in  Fig.  18  where  the  first 
break-step  is  shown  with  an  arrow.  The  break-step  is  always  given 


by  summing  up  the  coordinates ;  thus,  the  paths  here  being 


3,2 
-2,3 


by  summing  the  columns  we  get  (1,  5),  that  is  (1,  -1).    The  re- 
sulting square  is,  of  course,  identical  with  Fig.  5. 

As  previously  stated,  this  square  being  pandiagonal,  it  may  be 


312 


THE  MONIST. 


commenced  in  any  of  its  thirty-six  cells,  and  by  using  the  same 
methods  as  before,  different  aspects  of  Fig.  5  will  be  produced. 
Also,  since  by  this  method  complementary  pairs  are  always  sepa- 


7 


B 


D 


Fig.   18. 


Fig.   19. 


rated  by  a  step  (n/2,  n/2),  any  of  the  thirty-six  squares  thus  formed 
may  be  made  associated  by  the  method  described  in  The  Monist, 
Vol.  XX,  No.  3,  page  443,  under  the  heading  "Magic  Squares  by 


S3 


/S 


ZJ 


/o6 


/6 


/so 


7 


/OS 


/6o 


22 


26 


sz 


"7 


6s 


/z 


zs 


so 


/£// 


36 


/Z2 


Fig.  20. 

Complementary  Differences,"2  viz.,  Divide  the  square  into  four  quar- 
ters as  shown  in  Fig.  19 ;  leave  A  untouched,  reflect  B,  invert  C  and 

2  Errata  in  this  article :  p.  440,  footnote,  and  p.  443,  fourth  line  from  top 
of  page,  instead  of  "for  all  orders  =  4^+2''  read  "for  orders  wherein  n  is  of 
the  general  form  4/>+2."— Page  44,  last  line,  for  "order  8n"  read  "this  class." 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 


313 


reflect  and  invert  D.  For  this  concise  and  elegant  method  of  chang- 
ing the  relative  positions  of  the  complementary  couplets  in  a  square 
we  are  indebted  to  Dr.  Planck. 

The  next  square  in  order  is  1(X    The  series  of  numbers  used 
is  given  on  page  305  and  their  rearrangement  in  proper  cyclic  order 


" 


7 


/OS 


66 


/6o 


s6 


62 


7 


/o6 


/SS 


/z 


/39 


Z2, 


'6s 


/3S 


20 


/'S 


/0 


AT* 


S2, 


26 


36 


/OS 


/£/ 


30 


AT 


$7 


/sz 


/22 


"3 


'26 


,6 


so 


Fig.  21. 

for  direct  entry  may  be  found  as  before  in  the  continuous  diagonal 
of  its  magic  rectangle.  The  sequence  shown  in  Fig.  11  is  1,  2,  3,  4, 
9,  13,  12,  11,  10,  5,  and  the  complete  rearrangement  of  the  series  in 
accordance  therewith  is  given  in  Fig.  20.  Various  102  magics  may 


be  made  by  using  this  series  with  different  paths.    The  paths 


z/ 

z 

3 

¥ 

'7 

/6 

/s 

<? 

/£ 

/ 

20 

/& 

/<$ 

3~ 

6 

7 

'V 

& 

will  produce  Fig.  15,  and 


5,  2 

2,5 


5,4 
-4,5 


Fig.  22. 

will  make  Fig.  21,  which  is  equiva- 


lent  to  Fig.  15  in  its  ornate  features. 

These  squares  and  all  similarly  constructed  larger  ones  of  these 
orders  may  be  changed  to  the  form  of  association  wherein  the  com- 
plementary couplets  are  evenly  balanced  around  the  center  of  the 


THE  MONIST. 


square,  by  the  method  previously  explained.  It  will  be  unnecessary 
to  prolong  the  present  article  by  giving  any  examples  of  larger 
squares  of  this  class,  but  the  simple  forms  of  magic  rectangles  for 


2$ 

2 

Z/ 

^ 

fa 

6 

'7 

<? 

& 

/o 

'Z 

/ 

22 

<3 

20 

5- 

/<? 

7 

/6 

/& 

'# 

// 

Fig.  23. 


29 

Z 

*7 

t 

25 

6 

25 

s 

& 

zo 

// 

/<? 

/$ 

/ 

2# 

3 

26 

c5~ 

2^ 

7 

22 

Zf 

SO 

/& 

/z 

// 

Fig.  24. 

182  and  222  and  262  magics,  shown  in  Figs.  22,  23  and  24,  may  be 
of  some  assistance  to  those  who  desire  to  devote  further  study  to 
these  interesting  squares.3 

W.  S.  ANDREWS. 

L.  S.  FRIERSON. 


A  NEW  THEORY  OF  INVENTION. 

A  Russian  engineer,  P.  K.  von  Engelmeyer  of  Moscow  ( Peters- 
burger  Chaussee  42),  has  published  a  little  book  on  invention  and 
its  significance  in  our  industrial  life  under  the  title  Der  Dreiakt  (Ber- 
lin, Carl  Heymann's  Verlag)  in  which  he  claims  that  man  is  not 
only  a  political  being  (£<5o»>  iroAmKov)  as  Aristotle  claims,  but  also 
and  mainly  a  technical  being  (£woi/  TCXVIKOV),  and  he  means  it  in  the 
same  sense  in  which  Franklin  called  man  a  "tool-making  animal."1 

Mr.  Engelmeyer  defines  technique  as  the  art  of  reproducing 
artificially  or  intentionally  certain  desired  phenomena  (p.  17)  and 
he  calls  attention  to  the  fact  that  we  are  surrounded  by  the  products 
of  invention.  Our  clothes,  the  light  and  heat  in  our  houses,  our  mode 
of  traveling,  in  short,  all  that  is  called  culture  and  civilization  has 

"More  generally,  if  p,  q  are  relative  primes,  the  square  of  order  pq  will 
be  magic  on  its  pq  rows,  pq  columns  and  2pq  diagonals,  and  at  the  same  time 
/>2-ply  and  #-2ply,  if  it  be  constructed  with  the  paths  I  p,  q  I,  and  the  period 

I  Q>  P  I 

be  taken  from  the  continuous  diagonal  of  the  magic  rectangle  pXq-  The  limi- 
tations are  dictated  by  the  magic  rectangle.  Evidently  p  and  q  must  both  be 
>  i,  and  consecutive  numbers  must  fail  if  the  order  is  =  2  (mod.  4)  ;  in  all 
other  cases  consecutive  numbers  will  suffice.  c.  P. 

1  See  the  author's  The  Philosophy  of  the  Tool,  p.  i. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  315 

been  invented  at  various  times.  Some  inventions  have  been  made 
by  conscious  endeavor,  others  by  accident. 

Our  author  distinguishes  four  characteristics  of  invention:  (1) 
its  artificial  nature — man  interferes  with  natural  conditions  and  in- 
troduces a  human  element  into  them:  (2)  teleology — inventions 
must  be  designed,  they  must  serve  a  purpose;  (3)  surprise,  by 
which  word  our  author  means  that  they  must  be  something  new  or 
original ;  we  do  not  call  invention  what  is  merely  an  application  of 
former  experience;  (4)  unity — every  invention  is  a  kind  of  a  sys- 
tem, an  organic  whole,  and  the  members  must  be  integral  parts  of 
a  new  entirety.  Discovery  is  somewhat  different  from  invention, 
but  there  is  a  domain  which  belongs  practically  to  both  invention 
and  discovery.  Newton's  law  of  gravitation  is  a  discovery,  but 
mathematical  formulas  are  both. 

Mr.  Engelmeyer  quotes  Goethe  approvingly  when  he  says: 
"man  does  not  experience  or  enjoy  without  at  the  same  time  being 
productive,"  thus  implying  that  invention  is  an  indispensable  ele- 
ment in  human  existence.  There  are  three  fields  of  human  activity. 
When  man  devotes  his  efforts  to  purposes  of  utility,  the  result  is 
called  invention ;  when  his  efforts  are  devoted  to  cognition,  the  result 
is  called  discovery;  when  this  result  serves  esthetical  pleasure  it  is 
called  a  work  of  art.  Just  as  all  three  domains  are  ultimately  one, 
so  there  must  be  but  one  theory  of  invention  which  our  author  calls 
by  the  Greek  name  "Heurology,"  and  in  so  far  as  it  expresses  this 
union  he  calls  it  an  act  of  three,  or  in  German  Dreiakt. 

This  theory  of  the  Dreiakt  is  the  subject  of  the  main  part  of 
the  book,  and  the  author  has  consulted  the  patent  laws  of  different 
nations  for  details  and  illustrations.  From  the  standpoint  of  his 
conception  he  distinguishes  between  the  product  and  the  method 
of  an  invention;  the  former  is  the  effect  accomplished,  the  latter  is 
the  arrangement  of  parts,  the  combination  of  substances  in  definite 
proportions,  the  way  in  which  substances  are  treated  to  change  their 
nature.  The  patent  lawyer  must  consider  the  principle  which  com- 
prises the  effect  together  with  the  way  in  which  it  is  produced.  Ex- 
amples are  furnished  by  the  sewing  machine,  the  bicycle,  hydraulic 
systems,  aeronautics,  fire  arms,  chemical  inventions,  cement,  ex- 
plosives, photography,  Bessemer  steel,  etc. 

The  concluding  chapter  of  the  book  is  devoted  to  the  applica- 
tion of  the  Dreiakt  to  patent  laws  and  technical  instruction.  The 
universality  of  the  principle  of  the  Dreiakt  finds  appreciation  in  the 
proposition  that  the  human  will  itself  is  a  Dreiakt.  Our  auther 


316  THE  MONIST. 

gives  credit  to  O.  Schanze  who  has  published  his  views  on  the 
same  subject  under  the  title  Beitrdge  zur  Lehre  von  der  Patent- 
fdhigkeit,  fascicle  2,  pages  243-255  (Berlin,  Siemens,  1904).  He 
uses  the  term  Dreiakt  in  a  slightly  different  sense  and  speaks  of  three 
fundamental  energies:  (1)  intention  or  will,  (2)  reflection  or  knowl- 
edge, (3)  practical  skill.  These  characterize  every  act  of  creation 
as  a  Dreiakt,  (1)  the  aim  which  constitutes  the  teleology  of  the 
work,  (2)  the  plan  or  design  which  logically  determinates  the  work 
and  (3)  its  execution.  Schanze  applies  them  to  practical  problems, 
especially  to  these  three:  a,  Who  among  several  collaborators  is  the 
author  of  the  invention  and  who  merely  an  assistant;  b,  how  far 
in  its  application  is  an  invention  entitled  to  protection  by  patent; 
and  c,  at  what  state  of  completion  does  an  invention  acquire  the  right 
to  be  patented.  p.  c. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  AND  NOTES. 

THE  PERIPLUS  OF  THE  ERYTHRAEAN  SEA.  By  Wilfred  H.  Schoff.  New  York : 
Longmans,  Green  and  Company,  1912.  Pp.  323.  Price  $2.00  net. 

"Periplus"  means  circumnavigation  and  may  be  freely  translated  "log 
book"  or  "description  of  a  sea  voyage."  There  are  several  antique  books 
which  bear  the  same  title,  and  the  present  work  refers  to  that  body  of  water 
which  in  modern  times  is  known  as  the  Indian  Ocean,  together  with  the  Red 
Sea  and  the  Persian  Gulf.  This  record  describes  the  voyage  from  place  to 
place  of  an  ancient  merchant  vessel  and  is  of  great  interest  in  the  history  of 
trading.  The  book  itself  is  not  long.  It  contains  only  28  pages  of  English 
text,  but  the  translation  has  been  made  with  great  care.  Very  full  notes  ex- 
plain the  terms  used,  the  merchandise  traded  and  the  historical  connections, 
and  these  cover  pages  50  and  282 ;  tables  are  appended  listing  articles  of  trade 
and  rulers  mentioned  and  dates  variously  assigned  to  the  original,  a  map 
indicates  the  ports  touched  at  and  helps  the  readers  to  understand  the  geog- 
raphy of  our  travelers.  The  book  is  furnished  with  a  very  thorough  topical 
index  covering  thirty  two-columned  pages.  The  work  is  creditable  to  the 
spirit  of  the  Commercial  Museum  of  Philadelphia,  which  has  brought  it  out. 
W.  P.  Wilson,  the  director  of  the  Philadelphia  museums,  says  in  his  foreword : 

"The  Periplus  of  the  Erythraean  Sea  is  the  first  record  of  organized  trad- 
ing with  the  nations  of  the  East,  in  vessels  built  and  commanded  by  subjects 
of  the  Western  world.  The  notes  add  great  interest,  giving  as  they  do  an  ex- 
haustive survey  of  the  international  trade  between  the  great  empires  of  Rome, 
Parthia,  India  and  China,  together  with  a  collection  of  facts  touching  the 
early  trade  of  a  number  of  other  countries  of  much  interest."  K 


THE  INDIVIDUAL  AND  REALITY.    By  Edward  Douglas  Fawcett.    New  York: 

Longmans,  Green  &  Co.,  1909.    Pp.  449. 

The  author  writes  as  one  having  authority.  He  considers  himself  a  free 
lance,  since  he  is  independent  of  any  school  of  philosophy  or  religion,  and 
therefore  "free  to  ignore  all  traditions  and  conventions  and  go  straight  to 
reality  in  the  search  for  truth."  The  present  volume  is  intended  to  supersede 
a  former  one  to  which  he  refers  as  "my  Riddle."  This  former  work  was  read 
with  enormous  satisfaction  by  the  late  Prof.  William  James,  and  the  fact  that 
this  same  thinker  considers  his  book  "as  a  great  and  powerful  agency  in  the 
spreading  of  truth"  is  regarded  by  the  author  as  sufficient  justification  for  its 
appearance.  Mr.  Fawcett  credits  the  source  of  his  thinking  to  the  anti- 


318  THE   MONIST. 

Hegelian  thought  of  Schelling  and  Schopenhauer,  being  allied  to  the  former's 
"immemorial  being"  and  Bain's  doctrine  of  relativity.  He  has  not  read  Berg- 
son  with  whom  his  results  in  part  seem  to  agree.  In  this  later  work  he  has 
abandoned  the  monadology  of  his  former  production,  replacing  it  with  a  new 
form  of  idealism.  Some  of  the  novelties  of  the  former  work  are  here  retained. 
Part  I  is  an  introduction  to  metaphysics ;  Part  II  treats  of  the  individual  and 
his  universe,  appearances,  and  the  individual  in  his  relation  to  the  organism, 
nature  as  a  whole,  and  to  himself.  Part  III  deals  with  ultimate  questions, 
such  as  the  ground  of  appearance,  the  evolution  of  nature  and  individuals, 
birth,  death,  destiny  and  God.  p 


PROTESTANT  THOUGHT  BEFORE  KANT.     By  Arthur  Cushman  M'Giffert.    New 

York:  Charles  Scribner's  Sons,  1911.  Pp.  261.  Price,  75  cents  net. 
In  this  volume  dedicated  to  Adolf  Harnack,  the  author's  teacher  and 
friend,  Professor  M'Giffert,  of  Union  Theological  Seminary  of  New  York, 
traces  the  development  of  Protestantism  from  the  time  of  its  early  workings 
in  medieval  Christianity  to  that  of  the  great  Konigsberg  philosopher.  This 
includes  a  discussion  of  the  leaders  of  the  Reformation  in  all  countries,  Zwingli, 
Melanchthon,  Calvin;  also  the  radical  anabaptists  and  socianians.  The  Prot- 
estant phase  of  scholasticism  is  discussed,  and  pietism  in  Germany,  England 
and  New  England.  The  book  closes  with  a  chapter  on  rationalism  in  its  var- 
ious phases  as  found  in  England,  France,  Germany  and  America.  Professor 
M'Giffert's  book  is  the  sixth  volume  in  a  series  entitled  "Studies  in  Theol- 
ogy" which  are  intended  as  aids  to  interpretation  in  biblical  criticism,  pri- 
marily for  the  use  of  ministers  and  theological  students,  but  still  the  needs  of 
the  general  reader  are  kept  in  view  so  that  the  works  shall  not  become  too 
technical.  P 


UEBER  KLASSIKER  UND  PHILOSOPHEN  DER  NEUZEIT.    By  Julius  Rupp.  Leipsic: 

Eckardt,  1910.    Pp.  796  .  Price  6m. 

This  is  the  third  volume  of  Rupp's  collected  works  which  are  to  appear 
in  twelve  volumes,  and  have  been  edited  by  P.  C.  Elsenhans.  Each  volume 
has  a  separate  introduction  by  the  editor.  The  present  one  on  the  classicists 
and  modern  philosophers  contains  three  different  collections  of  Rupp's  essays. 
The  first  set,  from  Lessing  to  Hegel,  are  on  subjects  relating  to  Lessing,  Kant, 
Herder,  Spinoza,  Schiller,  Fichte  and  Schleiermacher.  The  second  collection, 
bearing  the  general  title  "Contemporary  Philosophy,"  discusses  subjects  re- 
lating to  natural  science,  controversies  about  the  soul,  macrocosm,  and  micro- 
cosm, the  relations  of  soul  to  body,  philosophy,  theology,  religion  of  the 
spirit;  and  devotes  special  chapters  to  Emerson,  Gioberti  and  Alexander  Bain. 
This  volume  contains  also  Rupp's  "Sketches  of  a  Thinker."  p 


THE  PHENOMENOLOGY  OF  MIND.     By  G.  W.  F.  Hegel.    Tr.  by  /.  B.  Baillie. 

2  vols.    London:  Sonnenschein,  1910.     Pp.  823.     Price  21  s.  net. 
This  translation  of  Hegel's  Phenomenology  is  one  number  of  Sonnen- 
schein's  "Library  of  Philosophy"  edited  by  Dr.  J.  H.  Muirhead.    The  object 
of  the  series  is  to  familiarize  English  readers  with  results  of  modern  philo- 


BOOK  REVIEWS  AND  NOTES.  319 

sophical  thought,  admitting  that  in  this  respect  Germany  has  far  excelled 
England.  The  editor's  purpose,  however,  besides  bringing  German  philosophy 
to  English  thinkers,  is  to  furnish  a  systematized  philosophical  library  in  which 
English  philosophy  will  receive  the  consideration  due  it,  as  its  significance 
has  been  largely  ignored  by  the  German  schools.  /> 


DAVID  HUME,  HANS  LIV  OG  HANS  FILOSOFI.    Af  Anton  Thomsen.    Copenhagen : 

Nordiske  Forfatteres  Forlag,  1911.  Pp.  458.  Price  1.65  kr. 
Professor  Anton  Thomsen  of  the  University  of  Copenhagen  is  preparing 
an  extremely  comprehensive  work  on  the  subject  of  this  great  English  phi- 
losopher. The  first  volume  appeared  during  last  winter,  and  after  a  few 
introductory  pages  calling  attention  to  the  bicentenary  of  David  Hume's  birth, 
takes  up  in  its  first  book  the  philosopher's  life  and  works,  and  in  the  second 
book  his  epistemology  and  psychology.  The  philosophical  critique  is  made 
with  due  reference  to  the  contemporary  thinkers  of  all  lands  in  connection 
with  the  philosophy  of  past  centuries.  p 


DEVOLUTION  DE  LA  MEMOiRE.  Par  Henri  Pitron.  Paris:  Flammarion,  1910. 
Pp.  360.  Price  3.50  fr. 

This  book  treats  of  the  extent  of  the  domain  of  the  memory  and  the  re- 
lations of  the  phenomena  of  inorganic  memory  to  those  of  psychic  memory ; 
of  the  forms  which  memory  assumes  in  all  the  steps  of  the  evolution  of  ani- 
mals and  the  continuity  of  the  series  when  passing  from  brute  creation  to 
man;  of  the  aspects  and  limitations  of  human  memory,  the  cause  of  its  diffi- 
culties and  its  probable  future.  The  discussion  of  these  points  is  based  on  the 
collection  of  facts  actually  established  by  objective  psychology,  human  and 
comparative. 

The  conclusion  drawn  is  both  pessimistic  and  optimistic:  pessimistic,  be- 
cause it  sees  no  chance  for  the  memory  of  men  regarded  individually  to  in- 
crease in  capacity,  and  because  the  utilization  of  the  traces  left  by  collective 
memory  (i.  e.,  presented  by  published  material)  seems  likely  to  become  more 
and  more  difficult;  optimistic,  in  that  the  conservation  of  many  recollections 
will  become  less  and  less  necessary  in  the  progress  of  scientific  classification 
which  will  make  possible  the  substitution  of  the  knowledge  of  a  small  number 
of  general  laws  for  that  of  a  large  number  of  particular  facts.  p 


DAS  KUNFTIGE  JAHRHUNDERT  DER  PsYCHOLociE.  Von  G.  Heymans.  Aus  dem 
Niederlandischen  tibersetzt  von  H.  Pol.  Leipsic:  Earth,  1911.  Pp. 
52.  Price  i  m.  20. 

Prof.  G.  Heymans,  retiring  rector  of  the  Groningen  University,  has  pub- 
hished  his  oration  in  the  translation  of  Mr.  H.  Pol,  the  German  teacher  ot 
the  same  university.  It  bears  the  title  "The  Future  Century  of  Psychology," 
and  insists  that  while  progress  is  rapid  in  other  branches  the  development  of 
psychology  ought  not  to  be  neglected  because  it  is  more  important  than  our 
progress  in  inventions.  The  main  subjects  of  psychology  refer  to  the  nature 
of  our  own  self,  our  relation  to  others  and  toward  the  ultimate  foundation  of 
the  world.  He  finds  that  much  is  to  be  done  and  much  has  been  neglected 


32O  THE  MONIST. 

in  former  ages.  In  opposition  to  the  common  view  that  competition  and  war 
are  necessary,  that  mankind  is  bad  at  the  core,  he  quotes  Frederick  the  Great 
as  having  said  of  a  prominent  educator :  "Ah,  mon  cher  Sulzer,  vous  ne  con- 
naissez  pas  assez  cette  maudite  race,  a  laquelle  nous  appartenons !"  In  oppo- 
sition to  the  current  view  he  expects  that  the  future  will  more  and  more 
restrict  competition  and  war,  and  criticizes  the  idea  that  they  are  necessary 
for  the  amelioration  of  the  race;  that  if  the  principle  were  reasonable  cattle 
breeders  and  hunters  might  just  as  well  introduce  it  into  the  artificial  methods 
of  producing  higher  and  better  breeds,  but  what  would  we  think  of  a  hunter 
who  would  make  his  hounds  quarrel  about  a  piece  of  meat  in  a  fierce  fight  in 
which  half  of  them  would  lose  their  lives,  and  this  simply  for  the  amelioration 
of  the  race?  He  ends  his  oration  by  quoting  the  words  of  a  mystic  thinker, 
"I  trust  that  all  will  yet  be  good."  K 


In  Hamburg,  the  place  of  the  first  monistic  congress,  a  free  religious 
society  has  been  founded  which  proposes  to  do  a  propaganda  for  a  rational 
world  conception.  Their  aims  are  through  religious  devotion  to  cultivate  the 
true,  the  good  and  the  beautiful.  In  politics  they  favor  separation  of  church 
from  state  and  of  school  from  church.  Their  secretary  is  Bruno  Heyer,  and 
their  treasurer  Adolf  Dunkel.  K 


The  well-known  activity  of  the  Leipsic  publishing  house  of  Diirr  is  seen 
by  constant  additional  contributions  to  its  Philosophische  Bibliothek,  and  the 
value  of  its  productions  is  attested  by  the  height  to  which  the  number  of  its 
editions  reaches.  Among  its  1910  publications,  besides  the  seventh  edition  of 
Baensch's  translation  of  Spinoza's  Ethics,  we  have  an  edition  by  Johannes 
Schubert  of  Wilhelm  von  Humboldt's  selected  philosophical  writings  and  the 
Definitions  of  Christian  Wolff  collected  by  Julius  Baumann  for  the  purpose  of 
serving  as  collateral  reading  in  the  study  of  Kant.  The  centennial  of  the 
Berlin  University  has  been  celebrated  by  this  enterprising  house  by  a  volume 
introduced  by  Edouard  Spranger  and  containing  the  addresses  of  Fichte, 
Schleiermacher  and  Steffins  on  "The  Nature  of  the  University,"  written  or 
delivered  at  the  time  of  its  opening.  A  second  edition  of  Dr.  Otto  Apelt's 
German  translation  of  Plato's  Thcaetetus  bears  the  date  of  1911,  and  purports 
to  be  an  entirely  new  translation  of  the  dialogue.  (Baruch  de  Spinoza,  Ethik, 
iibers.  von  Otto  Baensch;  Fichte,  Schleiermacher,  Steffens  uber  das  Wesen 
der  Universit'dt,  her.  von  Edouard  Spranger ;  Wilhelm  von  Humboldts  ausge- 
wdhlte  philosophische  Schriften,  her.  von.  Johannes  Schubert;  Wolff sche 
Begriffsbestimmungen,  her.  von  Julius  Baumann ;  Platons  Dialog  Theatet, 
iibers.  von  Dr.  Otto  Apelt.)  P 


The  scientific  publishing  house  of  A.  Hermann  and  Son,  at  Paris,  are 
publishing  a  French  translation  of  the  sixth  German  edition  of  Prof.  W. 
Nernst's  large  work  on  theoretical  chemistry.  It  is  translated  by  A.  Corvisy, 
under  the  title  Traite*  de  chimie  gtnerale.  The  first  part  is  issued  this  year, 
dealing  with  the  general  properties  of  bodies  and  atoms  and  molecules,  p 


VOL.  XXII.  JULY,  1912.  NO.  3 

THE  MONIST 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON,1 

i. 

~^HE  classification  of  philosophies  is  effected,  as  a  rule, 
JL  either  by  their  methods  or  by  their  results:  "empirical" 
and  "a  priori''  is  a  classification  by  methods,  "realist"  and 
"idealist"  is  a  classification  by  results.  An  attempt  to  clas- 
sify Bergson's  philosophy  in  either  of  these  ways  is  hardly 
likely  to  be  successful,  since  it  cuts  across  all  the  recognized 
divisions. 

But  there  is  another  way  of  classifying  philosophies, 
less  precise,  but  perhaps  more  helpful  to  the  non-philo- 
sophical ;  in  this  way,  the  principle  of  division  is  according 
to  the  predominant  desire  which  has  led  the  philosopher 
to  philosophize.  Thus  we  shall  have  philosophies  of  feel- 
ing, inspired  by  the  love  of  happiness;  theoretical  philos- 
ophies, inspired  by  the  love  of  knowledge;  and  practical 
philosophies,  inspired  by  the  love  of  action. 

Among  philosophies  of  feeling  we  shall  place  all  those 
which  are  primarily  optimistic  or  pessimistic,  all  those  that 
offer  schemes  of  salvation  or  try  to  prove  that  salvation  is 
impossible ;  to  this  class  belong  most  religious  philosophies. 
Among  theoretical  philosophies  we  shall  place  most  of  the 
great  systems ;  for  though  the  desire  for  knowledge  is  rare, 
it  has  been  the  source  of  most  of  what  is  best  in  philosophy. 
Practical  philosophies,  on  the  other  hand,  will  be  those 

JThe  abbreviations  of  the  titles  of  the  works  of  M.  Bergson  referred  to 
are:  C.E.,  Creative  Evolution;  M.  and  M.,  Matter  and  Memory;  Tand  F.  W., 
Time  and  Free  Will.  The  references  are  to  the  English  translations  of  M. 
Bergson's  books. 


322  THE  MONIST. 

which  regard  action  as  the  supreme  good,  considering  hap- 
piness an  effect  and  knowledge  a  mere  instrument  of  suc- 
cessful activity.  Philosophies  of  this  type  would  have  been 
common  among  Western  Europeans  if  philosophers  had 
been  average  men ;  as  it  is,  they  have  been  rare  until  recent 
times,  in  fact  their  chief  representatives  are  the  pragma- 
tists  and  M.  Bergson.  In  the  rise  of  this  type  of  philosophy 
we  may  see,  as  M.  Bergson  himself  does,  the  revolt  of  the 
modern  man  of  action  against  the  authority  of  Greece,  and 
more  particularly  of  Plato;  or  we  may  connect  it,  as  Dr. 
Schiller  apparently  would,  with  imperialism  and  the  motor- 
car. The  modern  world  calls  for  such  a  philosophy,  and 
the  success  which  it  has  achieved  is  therefore  not  surpris- 
ing. 

M.  Bergson's  philosophy,  unlike  most  of  the  systems  of 
the  past,  is  dualistic:  the  world,  for  him,  is  divided  into 
two  disparate  portions,  on  the  one  hand  life,  on  the  other 
matter,  or  rather  that  inert  something  which  the  intellect 
views  as  matter.  The  whole  universe  is  the  clash  and  conflict 
of  two  opposite  motions:  life,  which  climbs  upward,  and 
matter,  which  falls  downward.  Life  is  one  great  force, 
one  vast  vital  impulse,  given  once  for  all  from  the  begin- 
ning of  the  world,  meeting  the  resistance  of  matter,  strug- 
gling to  break  a  way  through  matter,  learning  gradually 
to  use  matter  by  means  of  organization;  divided  by  the 
obstacles  it  encounters  into  diverging  currents,  like  the 
wind  at  the  street-corner ;  partly  subdued  by  matter  through 
the  very  adaptations  which  matter  forces  upon  it;  yet  re- 
taining always  its  capacity  for  free  activity,  struggling 
always  to  find  new  outlets,  seeking  always  for  greater  lib- 
erty of  movement  amid  the  opposing  walls  of  matter. 

Evolution  is  not  primarily  explicable  by  adaptation  to 
environment ;  adaptation  explains  only  the  turns  and  twists 
of  evolution,  like  the  windings  of  a  road  approaching  a 
town  through  hilly  country.  But  this  simile  is  not  quite 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON.  323 

adequate;  there  is  no  town,  no  definite  goal,  at  the  end  of 
the  road  along  which  evolution  travels.  Mechanism  and 
teleology  suffer  from  the  same  defect:  both  suppose  that 
there  is  no  essential  novelty  in  the  world.  Mechanism 
regards  the  future  as  implicit  in  the  past,  since  it  believes 
the  future  to  be  calculable ;  teleology  also,  since  it  believes 
that  the  end  to  be  achieved  can  be  known  in  advance,  denies 
that  any  essential  novelty  is  contained  in  the  result. 

As  against  both  these  views,  though  with  more  sym- 
pathy for  teleology  than  for  mechanism,  M.  Bergson  main- 
tains that  evolution  is  truly  creative,  like  the  work  of  an 
artist.  An  impulse  to  action,  an  undefined  want,  exists 
beforehand,  but  until  the  want  is  satisfied  it  is  impossible 
to  know  the  nature  of  what  will  satisfy  it.  For  example, 
we  may  suppose  some  vague  desire  in  sightless  animals 
to  be  able  to  be  aware  of  objects  before  they  were  in  con- 
tact with  them.  This  led  to  efforts  which  finally  resulted 
in  the  creation  of  eyes.  Sight  satisfied  the  desire,  but 
could  not  have  been  imagined  beforehand.  For  this  rea- 
son, evolution  is  unpredictable,  and  determinism  cannot 
refute  the  advocates  of  free  will. 

This  broad  outline  is  filled  in  by  an  account  of  the 
actual  development  of  life  on  the  earth.  The  first  division 
of  the  current  was  into  plants  and  animals:  plants  aimed 
at  storing  up  energy  in  a  reservoir,  animals  aimed  at  using 
energy  for  sudden  and  rapid  movements.  "The  same  im- 
petus/' he  says,  "that  has  led  the  animal  to  give  itself 
nerves  and  nerve  centers  must  have  ended,  in  the  plant, 
in  the  chlorophyllian  function"  (C.  E.,  p.  120).  But  among 
animals,  at  a  later  stage,  a  new  bifurcation  appeared:  in- 
stinct and  intellect  became  more  or  less  separated.  They 
are  never  wholly  without  each  other,  but  in  the  main  in- 
tellect is  the  misfortune  of  man,  while  instinct  is  seen  at 
its  best  in  ants,  bees,  and  Bergson.  The  division  between 
intellect  and  instinct  is  fundamental  in  his  philosophy,  much 


3^4 


THE  MONIST. 


of  which  is  a  kind  of  Sandford  and  Merton,  with  instinct 
as  the  good  boy  and  intellect  as  the  bad  boy. 

Instinct  at  its  best  is  called  intuition.  "By  intuition," 
he  says,  "I  mean  instinct  that  has  become  disinterested, 
selfconscious,  capable  of  reflecting  upon  its  object  and  of 
enlarging  it  indefinitely"  (C.  E.,  p.  186).  The  account  of 
the  doings  of  intellect  is  not  always  easy  to  follow,  but  if 
we  are  to  understand  Bergson  we  must  do  our  best. 

Intelligence  or  intellect,  "as  it  leaves  the  hands  of  na- 
ture, has  for  its  chief  object  the  inorganic  solid"  (C.  E., 
p.  162)  ;  it  can  only  form  a  clear  idea  of  the  discontinuous 
and  the  immobile  (pp.  163-4)  ;  its  concepts  are  outside  each 
other  like  objects  in  space,  and  have  the  same  stability  (p. 
169).  The  intellect  separates  in  space  and  fixes  in  time; 
it  is  not  made  to  think  evolution,  but  represent  becoming 
as  a  series  of  states  (p.  171).  "The  intellect  is  character- 
ized by  a  natural  inability  to  understand  life"  (p.  174)  ; 
geometry  and  logic,  which  are  its  typical  products,  are 
strictly  applicable  to  solid  bodies,  but  elsewhere  reason- 
ing must  be  checked  by  common  sense,  which,  as  Bergson 
truly  says,  is  a  very  different  thing  (p.  170).  Solid  bodies, 
it  would  seem,  are  something  which  mind  has  created  on 
purpose  to  apply  intellect  to  them,  much  as  it  has  created 
chess-boards  in  order  to  play  chess  on  them.  The  genesis 
of  intellect  and  the  genesis  of  material  bodies,  we  are  told, 
are  correlative:  both  have  been  developed  by  reciprocal 
adaptation  (p.  196).  "An  identical  process  must  have  cut 
out  matter  and  the  intellect,  at  the  same  time,  from  a  stuff 
that  contained  both"  (p.  210). 

This  conception  of  the  simultaneous  growth  of  matter 
and  intellect  is  ingenious,  and  deserves  to  be  understood. 
Broadly,  I  think,  what  is  meant  is  this:  Intellect  is  the 
power  of  seeing  things  as  separate  one  from  another,  and 
matter  is  that  which  is  separated  into  distinct  things.  In 
reality  there  are  no  separate  solid  things,  only  an  endless 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON.  325 

stream  of  becoming,  in  which  nothing  becomes  and  there 
is  nothing  that  this  nothing  becomes.  But  becoming  may 
be  a  movement  up  or  a  movement  down:  when  it  is  a 
movement  up  it  is  called  life,  when  it  is  a  movement  down 
it  is  what,  as  misapprehended  by  the  intellect,  is  called 
matter.  I  suppose  the  universe  is  shaped  like  a  cone,  with 
the  Absolute  at  the  vertex,  for  the  movement  up  brings 
things  together,  while  the  movement  down  separates  them, 
or  at  least  seems  to  do  so.  In  order  that  the  upward  mo- 
tion of  mind  may  be  able  to  thread  its  way  through  the 
downward  motion  of  the  falling  bodies  which  hail  upon 
it,  it  must  be  able  to  cut  out  paths  between  them;  thus  as 
intelligence  was  formed,  outlines  and  paths  appeared  (p. 
199),  and  the  primitive  flux  was  cut  up  into  separate  bod- 
ies. The  intellect  may  be  compared  to  a  carver,  but  it  has 
the  peculiarity  of  imagining  that  the  chicken  always  was 
the  separate  pieces  into  which  the  carving-knife  divides  it. 
"The  intellect,"  Bergson  says,  "always  behaves  as  if 
it  were  fascinated  by  the  contemplation  of  inert  matter. 
It  is  life  looking  outward,  putting  itself  outside  itself, 
adopting  the  ways  of  inorganized  nature  in  principle,  in 
order  to  direct  them  in  fact"  (p.  170).  If  we  may  be 
allowed  to  add  another  image  to  the  many  by  which  Berg- 
son's  philosophy  is  illustrated,  we  may  say  that  the  universe 
is  a  vast  funicular  railway,  in  which  life  is  the  train  that 
goes  up,  and  matter  is  the  train  that  goes  down.  The  in- 
tellect consists  in  watching  the  descending  train  as  it  passes 
the  ascending  train  in  which  we  are.  The  obviously  nobler 
faculty  which  concentrates  its  attention  on  our  own  train, 
is  instinct  or  intuition.  It  is  possible  to  leap  from  one  train 
to  the  other ;  this  happens  when  we  become  the  victims  of 
automatic  habit,  and  is  the  essence  of  the  comic.  Or  we 
can  divide  ourselves  into  parts,  one  part  going  up  and  one 
down;  then  only  the  part  going  down  is  comic.  But  in- 
tellect is  not  itself  a  descending  motion,  it  is  merely  an 


326  THE  MONIST. 

observation  of  the  descending  motion  by  the  ascending 
motion. 

Intellect,  which  separates  things,  is,  according  to 
Bergson,  a  kind  of  dream;  it  is  not  active,  as  all  our  life 
ought  to  be,  but  purely  contemplative.  When  we  dream, 
he  says,  our  self  is  scattered,  our  past  is  broken  into  frag- 
ments (p.  2i2),2  things  which  really  interpenetrate  each 
other  are  seen  as  separate  solid  units:  the  extra-spatial 
degrades  itself  into  spatiality  (p.  218),  which  is  nothing 
but  separateness.  Thus  all  intellect,  since  it  separates, 
tends  to  geometry,  and  logic,  which  deals  with  concepts 
that  lie  wholly  outside  each  other,  is  really  an  outcome  of 
geometry,  following  the  direction  of  materiality  (pages 
222-4).  Both  deduction  and  induction  require  spatial  in- 
tuition behind  them  (p.  225)  ;  "the  movement  at  the  end 
of  which  is  spatiality  lays  down  along  its  course  the  faculty 
of  induction,  as  well  as  that  of  deduction,  in  fact,  intellec- 
tuality entire."  It  creates  them  in  mind,  and  also  the  order 
in  things  which  the  intellect  finds  there  (p.  228).  Thus 
logic  and  mathematics  do  not  represent  a  positive  spiritual 
effort  (p.  224),  but  a  mere  somnambulism,  in  which  the 
will  is  suspended,  and  the  mind  is  no  longer  active.  In- 
capacity for  mathematics  is  therefore  a  sign  of  grace- 
fortunately  a  very  common  one. 

As  intellect  is  connected  with  space,  so  instinct  or  in- 
tuition is  connected  with  time.  It  is  one  of  the  noteworthy 
features  of  Bergson's  philosophy  that,  unlike  most  writers, 
he  regards  time  and  space  as  profoundly  dissimilar.  Space, 
the  characteristic  of  matter,  arises  from  a  dissection  of  the 
flux  which  is  really  illusory,  useful,  up  to  a  certain  point, 
in  practice,  but  utterly  misleading  in  theory.  Time,  on 
the  contrary,  is  the  essential  characteristic  of  life  or  mind. 
"Wherever  anything  lives/'  he  says,  "there  is,  open  some- 

2  It  is  noteworthy  that  elsewhere  Bergson  speaks  of  dreams  as.  giving  us 
duration  more  pure  than  in  waking  life  (T.  and  F.  W.,  p.  126). 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON.  327 

where,  a  register  in  which  time  is  being  inscribed"  (C.  E., 
p.  17).  But  the  time  here  spoken  of  is  not  mathematical 
time,  the  homogeneous  assemblage  of  mutually  external 
instants.  Mathematical  time,  according  to  Bergson,  is  re- 
ally a  form  of. space;  the  time  which  is  of  the  essence  of 
life  is  what  he  calls  duration.  This  conception  of  duration 
is  fundamental  in  his  philosophy;  it  appears  already  in  his 
earliest  book  Time  and  Free  Will,  and  it  is  necessary  to 
understand  it  if  we  are  to  have  any  comprehension  of  his 
system.  It  is,  however,  a  very  difficult  conception.  I  do 
not  fully  understand  it  myself,  and  therefore  I  cannot 
hope  to  explain  it  with  all  the  lucidity  which  it  doubtless 
deserves. 

"Pure  duration/'  we  are  told,  "is  the  form  which  our 
conscious  states  assume  when  our  ego  lets  itself  live,  when 
it  refrains  from  separating  its  present  state  from  its  former 
states"  (T.  and  F.  W.,  p.  100).  It  forms  the  past  and  the 
present  into  one  organic  whole,  where  there  is  mutual  pene- 
tration, succession  without  distinction  (ib.).  "Within  our 
ego,  there  is  succession  without  mutual  externality;  out- 
side the  ego,  in  pure  space,  there  is  mutual  externality 
without  succession"  (p.  108). 

"Questions  relating  to  subject  and  object,  to  their  dis- 
tinction and  their  union,  should  be  put  in  terms  of  time 
rather  than  of  space"  (M.  and  M.,  p.  77).  In  the  duration 
in  which  we  see  ourselves  acting,  there  are  dissociated  ele- 
ments ;  but  in  the  duration  in  which  we  act,  our  states  melt 
into  each  other  (M.  and  M.,  p.  243).  Pure  duration  is 
what  is  most  removed  from  externality  and  least  penetrated 
with  externality,  a  duration  in  which  the  past  is  big  with 
a  present  absolutely  new.  But  then  our  will  is  strained 
to  the  utmost;  we  have  to  gather  up  the  past  which  is 
slipping  away,  and  thrust  it  whole  and  undivided  into  the 
present.  At  such  moments  we  truly  possess  ourselves,  but 
such  moments  are  rare  (C.  E.,  pp.  210-211).  Duration  is 


328  THE  MONIST. 

the  very  stuff  of  reality,  which  is  perpetual  becoming,  never 
something  made  (C.E.,  p.  287). 

It  is  above  all  in  memory  that  duration  exhibits  itself, 
for  in  memory  the  past  survives  in  the  present.  Thus  the 
theory  of  memory  becomes  of  great  importance  in  Berg- 
son's  philosophy.  Matter  and  Memory  is  concerned  to 
show  the  relation  of  mind  and  matter,  of  which  both  are 
affirmed  to  be  real  (p.  vii),  by  an  analysis  of  memory, 
which  is  "just  the  intersection  of  mind  and  matter"  (p.xii). 

There  are,  to  begin  with,  two  radically  different  things, 
both  of  which  are  commonly  called  memory ;  the  clear  dis- 
tinction between  these  two  is  one  of  the  best  things  in  Berg- 
son.  "The  past  survives,"  he  says,  "under  two  distinct 
forms:  first,  in  motor  mechanisms;  secondly,  in  indepen- 
dent recollections"  (M.  and  M.,  p.  87).  For  example,  a 
man  is  said  to  remember  a  poem  if  he  can  repeat  it  by 
heart,  that  is  to  say,  if  he  has  acquired  a  certain  habit  or 
mechanism  enabling  him  to  repeat  a  former  action.  But 
he  might,  at  least  theoretically,  be  able  to  repeat  the  poem 
without  any  recollection  of  the  previous  occasions  on  which 
he  has  read  it ;  thus  there  is  no  consciousness  of  past  events 
involved  in  this  sort  of  memory.  The  second  sort,  which 
alone  really  deserves  to  be  called  memory,  is  exhibited  in 
recollections  of  separate  occasions  when  he  has  read  the 
poem,  each  unique  and  with  a  date.  Here  there  can  be  no 
question  of  habit,  since  each  event  only  occurred  once,  and 
had  to  make  its  impression  immediately.  It  is  suggested 
that  in  some  way  everything  that  has  happened  to  us  is 
remembered,  but  as  a  rule,  only  what  is  useful  comes  into 
consciousness.  Apparent  failures  of  memory,  it  is  argued, 
are  not  really  failures  of  the  mental  part  of  memory,  but 
of  the  motor  mechanism  for  bringing  memory  into  action. 
This  view  is  supported  by  a  discussion  of  brain  physiology 
and  the  facts  of  amnesia,  from  which  it  is  held  to  result 
that  true  memory  is  not  a  function  of  the  brain  (M.  and  M., 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON.  329 

p.  315).  The  past  must  be  acted  by  matter,  imagined  by 
mind  (M.  and  M.,  p.  298).  Memory  is  not  an  emanation 
of  matter;  indeed  the  contrary  would  be  nearer  the  truth 
if  we  mean  matter  as  grasped  in  concrete  perception,  which 
always  occupies  a  certain  duration  (M.  and  M.,  p.  237). 

"Memory  must  be,  in  principle,  a  power  absolutely  in- 
dependent of  matter.  If,  then,  spirit  is  a  reality,  it  is  here, 
in  the  phenomena  of  memory,  that  we  may  come  into  touch 
with  it  experimentally"  (M.  and  M.,  p.  81). 

At  the  opposite  end  from  pure  memory  Bergson  places 
pure  perception,  in  regard  to  which  he  adopts  an  ultra- 
realist  position.  "In  pure  perception,"  he  says,  "we  are 
actually  placed  outside  ourselves,  we  touch  the  reality  of 
the  object  in  an  immediate  intuition"  (p.  84).  So  com- 
pletely does  he  identify  perception  with  its  object  that  he 
almost  refuses  to  call  it  mental  at  all.  "Pure  perception," 
he  says,  "which  is  the  lowest  degree  of  mind — mind  with- 
out memory — is  really  part  of  matter,  as  we  understand 
matter"  (M.  and  M.,  p.  297).  Pure  perception  is  consti- 
tuted by  dawning  action,  its  actuality  lies  in  its  activity 
(M.  and  M.,  p.  74).  It  is  in  this  way  that  the  brain  be- 
comes relevant  to  perception,  for  the  brain  is  not  an  instru- 
ment of  representation,  but  an  instrument  of  action  (M. 
anl  M.,  p.  83).  The  function  of  the  brain  is  to  limit  our 
mental  life  to  what  is  practically  useful.  But  for  the  brain, 
one  gathers,  everything  would  be  perceived,  but  in  fact 
we  only  perceive  what  interests  us  (cf.  M.  and  M.,  p.  34). 
"The  body,  always  turned  towards  action,  has  for  its  essen- 
tial function  to  limit,  with  a  view  to  action,  the  life  of  the 
spirit"  (M.  and  M.,  p.  233).  It  is,  in  fact,  an  instrument 
of  choice. 

We  must  now  return  to  the  subject  of  instinct  or  intui- 
tion, as  opposed  to  intellect.  It  was  necessary  first  to  give 
some  account  of  duration  and  memory,  since  Bergson's 
theories  of  duration  and  memory  are  presupposed  in  his 


330  THE  MONIST. 

account  of  intuition.  In  man,  as  he  now  exists,  intuition  is 
the  fringe  or  penumbra  of  intellect :  it  has  been  thrust  out 
of  the  center  by  being  less  useful  in  action  than  intellect, 
but  it  has  deeper  uses  which  make  it  desirable  to  bring  it 
back  into  greater  prominence.  Bergson  wishes  to  make 
intellect  "turn  inwards  on  itself,  and  awaken  the  poten- 
tialities of  intuition  which  still  slumber  within  it"  (C.  E., 
p.  192).  The  relation  between  instinct  and  intellect  is 
compared  to  that  between  sight  and  touch.  Intellect,  we 
are  told,  will  not  give  knowledge  of  things  at  a  distance; 
indeed  the  function  of  science  is  said  to  be  to  explain  all 
perceptions  in  terms  of  touch. 

"Instinct  alone,  he  says,  "is  knowledge  at  a  distance. 
It  has  the  same  relation  to  intelligence  that  vision  has  to 
touch"  (C.  E.,  p.  177).  We  may  observe  in  passing  that, 
as  appears  in  many  passages,  Bergson  is  a  strong  visual- 
izer,  whose  thought  is  always  conducted  by  means  of  visual 
images.  Many  things  which  he  declares  to  be  necessities 
of  all  thought  are,  I  believe,  characteristic  of  visualizers, 
and  would  not  be  true  of  those  who  think  by  means  of 
auditory  images.  He  always  exalts  the  sense  of  sight  at 
the  expense  of  the  other  senses,  and  his  views  -on  space 
would  seem  to  be  largely  determined  by  this  fact.  I  shall 
return  to  this  question  at  a  later  stage. 

The  essential  characteristic  of  intuition  is  that  it  does 
not  divide  the  world  into  separate  things,  as  the  intellect 
does ;  although  Bergson  does  not  use  these  words,  we  might 
describe  it  as  synthetic  rather  than  analytic.  It  apprehends 
a  multiplicity,  but  a  multiplicity  of  interpenetrating  proc- 
esses, not  of  spatially  external  bodies.  There  are  in  truth 
no  things :  "things  and  states  are  only  views,  taken  by  our 
mind,  of  becoming.  There  are  no  things,  there  are  only 
actions"  (C.  E.,  p.  261).  This  view  of  the  world,  which 
appears  difficult  and  unnatural  to  intellect,  is  easy  and 
natural  to  intuition.  Memory  affords  an  instance  of  what 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON.  33! 

is  meant,  for  in  memory  the  past  lives  on  into  the  present 
and  interpenetrates  it.  Apart  from  mind,  the  world  would 
be  perpetually  dying  and  being  born  again;  the  past  would 
have  no  reality,  and  therefore  there  would  be  no  past.  It 
is  memory,  with  its  correlative  desire,  that  makes  the  past 
and  the  future  real  and  therefore  creates  true  duration 
and  true  time.  Intuition  alone  can  understand  this  min- 
gling of  past  and  future:  to  the  intellect  they  remain  ex- 
ternal, spatially  external  as  it  were,  to  one  another.  Under 
the  guidance  of  intuition,  we  perceive  that  "form  is  only 
a  snapshot  view  of  a  transition"  (C.  E.,  p.  319),  and  the 
philosopher  "will  see  the  material  world  melt  back  into 
a  single  flux"  (C.  E.,  p.  390). 

Closely  connected  with  the  merits  of  intuition  is  Berg- 
son's  doctrine  of  freedom  and  his  praise  of  action.  "In 
reality,"  he  says,  "a  living  being  is  a  center  of  action.  It 
represents  a  certain  sum  of  contingency  entering  into  the 
world,  that  is  to  say,  a  certain  quantity  of  possible  action" 
(C.  E.,  p.  276).  The  arguments  against  free  will  depend 
partly  upon  assuming  that  the  intensity  of  psychical  states 
is  a  quantity,  capable,  at  least  in  theory,  of  numerical  meas- 
urement ;  this  view  Bergson  undertakes  to  refute  in  the  first 
chapter  of  Time  and  Free  Will.  Partly  the  determinist 
depends,  we  are  told,  upon  a  confusion  between  true  dura- 
tion and  mathematical  time,  which  Bergson  regards  as 
really  a  form  of  space.  Partly,  again,  the  determinist  rests 
his  case  upon  the  unwarranted  assumption  that,  when  the 
state  of  the  brain  is  given,  the  state  of  the  mind  is  theoret- 
ically determinate.  Bergson  is  willing  to  admit  that  the 
converse  is  true,  that  is  to  say,  that  the  state  of  brain  is 
determinate  when  the  state  of  mind  is  given,  but  he  regards 
the  mind  as  more  differentiated  than  the  brain,  and  there- 
fore holds  that  many  different  states  of  mind  may  corres- 
pond to  one  state  of  brain.  He  concludes  that  real  free- 
dom is  possible:  "We  are  free  when  our  acts  spring  from 


332  THE  MONIST. 

our  whole  personality,  when  they  express  it,  when  they 
have  that  indefinable  resemblance  to  it  which  one  some- 
times finds  between  the  artist  and  his  work"  (T.  and  F.  W ., 
p.  172). 

In  the  above  outline,  I  have  in  the  main  endeavored 
merely  to  state  Bergson's  views,  without  giving  the  reasons 
adduced  by  him  in  favor  of  their  truth.  This  is  easier  than 
it  would  be  with  most  philosophers,  since  as  a  rule  he  does 
not  give  reasons  for  his  opinions,  but  relies  on  their  in- 
herent attractiveness,  and  on  the  charm  of  an  excellent 
style.  Like  the  advertisers  of  Oxo,  he  relies  upon  pictur- 
esque and  varied  statement,  and  an  apparent  explanation 
of  many  obscure  facts.  Analogies  and  similes,  especially 
form  a  very  large  part  of  the  whole  process  by  which  he  rec- 
ommends his  views  to  the  reader.  The  number  of  similes  for 
life  to  be  found  in  his  works  exceeds  the  number  in  any 
poet  known  to  me.  Life,  he  says,  is  like  a  shell  bursting 
into  fragments  which  are  again  shells  (C.  E.,  p.  103).  It 
is  like  a  sheaf  (ib.,  p.  104).  Initially,  it  was  "a  tendency 
to  accumulate  in  a  reservoir,  as  do  especially  the  green 
parts  of  vegetables"  (ib.,  p.  260).  But  the  reservoir  is  to 
be  filled  with  boiling  water  from  which  steam  is  issuing; 
"jets  must  be  gushing  out  unceasingly,  of  which  each,  fall- 
ing back,  is  a  world"  (ib.,  p.  261).  Again  "life  appears  in 
its  entirety  as  an  immense  wave  which,  starting  from  a 
center,  spreads  outwards,  and  which  on  almost  the  whole 
of  its  circumference  is  stopped  and  converted  into  oscilla- 
tion: at  one  single  point  the  obstacle  has  been  forced,  the 
impulsion  has  passed  freely"  (ib.,  p.  280).  Then  there  is 
the  great  climax  in  which  life  is  compared  to  a  cavalry 
charge.  "All  organized  beings,  from  the  humblest  to  the 
highest,  from  the  first  origins  of  life  to  the  time  in  which 
we  are,  and  in  all  places  as  in  all  times,  do  but  evidence  a 
single  impulsion,  the  inverse  of  the  movement  of  matter, 
and  in  itself  indivisible.  All  the  living  hold  together,  and 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON.  333 

all  yield  to  the  same  tremendous  push.  The  animal  takes 
its  stand  on  the  plant,  man  bestrides  animality,  and  the 
whole  of  humanity,  in  space  and  in  time,  is  one  immense 
army  galloping  beside  and  before  and  behind  each  of  us 
in  an  overwhelming  charge  able  to  beat  down  every  re- 
sistance and  to  clear  many  obstacles,  perhaps  even  death" 
(C.E.,  pp.  285-6). 

But  a  cool  critic,  who  feels  himself  a  mere  spectator, 
perhaps  an  unsympathetic  spectator,  of  the  charge  in  which 
man  is  mounted  upon  animality,  may  be  inclined  to  think 
that  calm  and  careful  thought  is  hardly  compatible  with 
this  form  of  exercise.  When  he  is  told  that  thought  is  a 
mere  means  of  action,  the  mere  impulse  to  avoid  obstacles 
in  the  field,  he  may  feel  that  such  a  view  is  becoming  in  a 
cavalry  officer,  but  not  in  a  philosopher,  whose  business, 
after  all,  is  with  thought:  he  may  feel  that  in  the  passion 
and  noise  of  violent  motion  there  is  no  room  for  the  fainter 
music  of  reason,  no  leisure  for  the  disinterested  contem- 
plation in  which  greatness  is  sought,  not  by  turbulence, 
but  by  the  greatness  of  the  universe  which  is  mirrored.  In 
that  case,  he  may  be  tempted  to  ask  whether  there  are  any 
reasons  for  accepting  such  a  restless  view  of  the  world. 
And  if  he  asks  this  question,  he  will  find,  if  I  am  not  mis- 
taken, that  there  is  no  reason  whatever  for  accepting  this 
view,  either  in  the  universe  or  in  the  writings  of  M.  Berg- 
son. 

ii. 

The  two  foundations  of  Bergson's  philosophy,  in  so 
far  as  it  is  more  than  an  imaginative  and  poetic  view  of  the 
world,  are  his  doctrines  of  space  and  time.  His  doctrine 
of  space  is  required  for  his  condemnation  of  the  intellect, 
and  if  he  fails  in  his  condemnation  of  the  intellect,  the  in- 
tellect will  succeed  in  its  condemnation  of  him,  for  between 
the  two  it  is  war  to  the  knife.  His  doctrine  of  time  is 


334  THE  MONIST. 

necessary  for  his  vindication  of  freedom,  for  his  escape 
from  what  William  James  called  a  "block  universe/'  for 
his  doctrine  of  a  perpetual  flux  in  which  there  is  nothing 
that  flows,  and  for  his  whole  account  of  the  relations  be- 
tween mind  and  matter.  It  will  be  well,  therefore,  in  criti- 
cism, to  concentrate  on  these  two  doctrines.  If  they  are 
true,  such  minor  errors  and  inconsistencies  as  no  philos- 
opher escapes  would  not  greatly  matter,  while  if  they  are 
false,  nothing  remains  except  an  imaginative  epic,  to  be 
judged  on  esthetic  rather  than  on  intellectual  grounds.  I 
shall  begin  with  the  theory  of  space,  as  being  the  simpler 
of  the  two. 

Bergson's  theory  of  space  occurs  fully  and  explicitly 
in  his  Time  and  Free  Will,  and  therefore  belongs  to  the 
oldest  parts  of  his  philosophy.  In  his  first  chapter,  he  con- 
tends that  greater  and  less  imply  space,  since  he  regards 
the  greater  as  essentially  that  which  contains  the  less.  He 
offers  no  arguments  whatever,  either  good  or  bad,  in  favor 
of  this  view ;  he  merely  exclaims,  as  though  he  were  giving 
an  obvious  reductio  ad  absurdum:  "As  if  one  could  still 
speak  of  magnitude  where  there  is  neither  multiplicity  nor 
space!"  (p.  9).  The  obvious  cases  to  the  contrary,  such  as 
pleasure  and  pain,  afford  him  much  difficulty,  yet  he  never 
doubts  or  re-examines  the  dogma  with  which  he  starts. 

In  his  next  chapter,  he  maintains  the  same  thesis  as 
regards  number.  "As  soon  as  we  wish  to  picture  number 
to  ourselves,"  he  says,  "and  not  merely  figures  or  words, 
we  are  compelled  to  have  recourse  to  an  extended  image" 
(p.  78),  and  "every  clear  idea  of  number  implies  a  visual 
image  in  space"  (p.  79).  These  two  sentences  suffice  to 
show,  as  I  shall  try  to  prove,  that  Bergson  does  not  know 
what  number  is,  and  has  himself  no  clear  idea  of  it.  This 
is  shown  also  by  his  definition:  "Number  may  be  defined 
in  general  as  a  collection  of  units,  or,  speaking  more  ex- 
actly, as  the  synthesis  of  the  one  and  the  many"  (p.  75). 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON.  335 

In  discussing  these  statements,  I  must  ask  the  reader's 
patience  for  a  moment  while  I  call  attention  to  some  dis- 
tinctions which  may  at  first  appear  pedantic,  but  are  really 
vital.  There  are  three  entirely  different  things  which  are 
confused  by  Bergson  in  the  above  statements,  namely :  ( i ) 
number,  the  general  concept  applicable  to  the  various  par- 
ticular numbers;  (2)  the  various  particular  numbers;  (3) 
the  various  collections  to  which  the  various  particular  num- 
bers are  applicable.  It  is  this  last  that  is  defined  by  Berg- 
son  when  he  says  that  number  is  a  collection  of  units.  The 
twelve  apostles,  the  twelve  tribes  of  Israel,  the  twelve 
months,  the  twelve  signs  of  the  zodiac,  are  all  collections 
of  units,  yet  no  one  of  them  is  the  number  12,  still  less  is  it 
number  in  general,  as  by  the  above  definition  it  ought  to 
be.  The  number  12,  obviously,  is  something  which  all 
these  collections  have  in  common,  but  which  they  do  not 
have  in  common  with  other  collections,  such  as  cricket 
elevens.  Hence  the  number  12  is  neither  a  collection  of 
twelve  terms,  nor  is  it  something  which  all  collections  have 
in  common;  and  number  in  general  is  a  property  of  12  or 
1 1  or  any  other  number,  but  not  of  the  various  collections 
that  have  twelve  terms  or  eleven  terms. 

Hence  when,  following  Bergson's  advice,  we  "have  re- 
course to  an  extended  image"  and  picture,  say,  twelve  dots 
such  as  are  obtained  by  throwing  double  sixes  at  dice,  we 
have  still  not  obtained  a  picture  of  the  number  12.  The 
number  12,  in  fact,  is  something  more  abstract  than  any 
picture.  Before  we  can  be  said  to  have  any  understanding 
of  the  number  12,  we  must  know  what  different  collections 
of  twelve  units  have  in  common,  and  this  is  something 
which  cannot  be  pictured  because  it  is  abstract.  Bergson 
only  succeeds  in  making  his  theory  of  number  plausible  by 
confusing  a  particular  collection  with  the  number  of  its 
terms,  and  this  again  with  number  in  general. 

The  confusion  is  the  same  as  if  we  confused  a  particular 


336  THE  MONIST. 

young  man  with  youth,  and  youth  with  the  general  concept 
"period  of  human  life,"  and  were  then  to  argue  that  because 
a  young  man  has  two  legs,  youth  must  have  two  legs,  and 
the  general  concept  "period  of  human  life"  must  have  two 
legs.  The  confusion  is  important  because,  as  soon  as  it  is 
perceived,  the  theory  that  number  or  particular  numbers 
can  be  pictured  in  space  is  seen  to  be  untenable.  This  not 
only  disproves  Bergson's  theory  as  to  number,  but  also 
his  more  general  theory  that  all  abstract  ideas  and  all  logic 
are  derived  from  space;  for  the  abstract  12,  the  common 
property  of  all  dozens  as  opposed  to  any  particular  dozen, 
though  it  is  never  present  to  his  mind,  is  obviously  con- 
ceivable and  obviously  capable  of  being  pictured  in  space. 
But  apart  from  the  question  of  numbers,  shall  we  admit 
Bergson's  contention  that  every  plurality  of  separate  units 
involves  space?  Some  of  the  cases  that  appear  to  contra- 
dict this  view  are  considered  by  him,  for  example  succes- 
sive sounds.  When  we  hear  the  steps  of  a  passer-by  in  the 
street,  he  says,  we  visualize  his  successive  positions ;  when 
we  hear  the  strokes  of  a  bell,  we  either  picture  it  swinging 
backwards  and  forwards,  or  we  range  the  successive 
sounds  in  an  ideal  space  (T.  and  F.  W .,  p.  86).  But  these 
are  mere  autobiographical  observations  of  a  visualizer, 
and  illustrate  the  remark  we  made  before,  that  Bergson's 
views  depend  upon  the  predominance  of  the  sense  of  sight 
in  him.  There  is  no  logical  necessity  to  range  the  strokes 
of  a  clock  in  an  imaginary  space:  most  people,  I  imagine, 
count  them  without  any  spatial  auxiliary.  Yet  no  reason 
is  alleged  by  Bergson  for  the  view  that  space  is  necessary. 
He  assumes  this  as  obvious,  and  proceeds  at  once  to  apply 
it  to  the  case  of  times.  Where  there  seem  to  be  different 
times  outside  each  other,  he  says,  the  times  are  pictured 
as  spread  out  in  space;  in  real  time,  such  as  is  given  by 
memory,  different  times  interpenetrate  each  other,  and  can- 
not be  counted  because  they  are  not  separate. 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON.  337 

The  view  that  all  separateness  implies  space  is  now 
supposed  established,  and  is  used  deductively  to  prove  that 
space  is  involved  wherever  there  is  obviously  separateness, 
however  little  other  reason  there  may  be  for  suspecting 
such  a  thing.  Thus  abstract  ideas,  for  example,  obviously 
exclude  each  other :  whiteness  is  different  from  blackness, 
health  is  different  from  sickness,  folly  is  different  from  wis- 
dom. Hence  all  abstract  ideas  involve  space ;  and  therefore 
logic,  which  uses  abstract  ideas,  is  an  offshot  of  geometry, 
and  the  whole  of  the  intellect  depends  upon  a  supposed 
habit  of  picturing  things  side  by  side  in  space.  This  con- 
clusion, upon  which  Bergson's  whole  condemnation  of  the 
intellect  rests,  is  based,  so  far  as  can  be  discovered,  entirely 
upon  a  personal  idiosyncrasy  mistaken  for  a  necessity  of 
thought,  I  mean  the  idiosyncrasy  of  visualizing  succes- 
sions as  spread  out  on  a  line.  The  instance  of  numbers 
shows  that,  if  Bergson  were  in  the  right,  we  could  never 
have  attained  to  the  abstract  ideas  which  are  supposed  to 
be  thus  impregnated  with  space;  and  conversely,  the  fact 
that  we  can  understand  abstract  ideas  (as  opposed  to  par- 
ticular things  which  exemplify  them)  seems  sufficient  to 
prove  that  he  is  wrong  in  regarding  the  intellect  as  impreg- 
nated with  space. 

One  of  the  bad  effects  of  an  anti-intellectual  philosophy, 
such  as  that  of  Bergson,  is  that  it  thrives  upon  the  errors 
and  confusions  of  the  intellect.  Hence  it  is  led  to  prefer 
bad  thinking  to  good,  to  declare  every  momentary  difficulty 
insoluble,  and  to  regard  every  foolish  mistake  as  revealing 
the  bankruptcy  of  intellect  and  the  triumph  of  intuition. 
There  are  in  Bergson's  works  many  allusions  to  mathe- 
matics and  science,  and  to  a  careless  reader  these  allusions 
may  seem  to  strengthen  his  philosophy  greatly.  As  re- 
gards science,  especially  biology  and  physiology,  I  am  not 
competent  to  criticize  his  interpretations.  But  as  regards 
mathematics,  he  has  deliberately  preferred  traditional  er- 


338  THE   MONIST. 

rors  in  interpretation  to  the  more  modern  views  which 
have  prevailed  among  mathematicians  for  the  last  half 
century.  In  this  matter,  he  has  followed  the  example  of 
most  philosophers.  In  the  eighteenth  and  early  nineteenth 
centuries,  the  infinitesimal  calculus,  though  well  developed 
as  a  method,  was  supported,  as  regards  its  foundations, 
by  many  fallacies  and  much  confused  thinking.  Hegel  and 
his  followers  seized  upon  these  fallacies  and  confusions,  to 
support  them  in  their  attempt  to  prove  all  mathematics 
self-contradictory.  Thence  the  Hegelian  account  of  these 
matters  passed  into  the  current  thought  of  philosophers, 
where  it  has  remained  long  after  the  mathematicians  have 
removed  all  the  difficulties  upon  which  the  philosophers 
rely.  And  so  long  as  the  main  object  of  philosophers  is  to 
show  that  nothing  can  be  learned  by  patience  and  detailed 
thinking,  but  that  we  ought  rather  to  worship  the  preju- 
dices of  the  ignorant  under  the  title  of  "reason"  if  we  are 
Hegelians,  or  of  "intuition"  if  we  are  Bergsonians,  so  long 
philosophers  will  take  care  to  remain  ignorant  of  what 
mathematicians  have  done  to  remove  the  errors  by  which 
Hegel  profited. 

Apart  from  the  question  of  number,  which  we  have  al- 
ready considered,  the  chief  point  at  which  Bergson  touches 
mathematics  is  his  rejection  of  what  he  calls  the  "cinemato- 
graphic" representation  of  the  world.  Mathematics  con- 
ceives change,  even  continuous  change,  as  constituted  by  a 
series  of  states ;  Bergson,  on  the  contrary,  contends  that  no 
series  of  states  can  represent  what  is  continuous,  and  that 
in  change  a  thing  is  never  in  any  state  at  all.  This  view- 
that  change  is  constituted  by  a  series  of  changing  states 
he  calls  cinematographic;  this  view,  he  says,  is  natural  to 
the  intellect,  but  is  radically  vicious.  True  change  can 
only  be  explained  by  true  duration;  it  involves  an  inter- 
penetration  of  past  and  present,  not  a  mathematical  suc- 
cession of  static  states.  This  is  what  is  called  a  "dynamic" 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON.  339 

instead  of  a  "static"  view  of  the  world.  The  question  is 
important,  and  in  spite  of  its  difficulty  we  cannot  pass 
it  by. 

Bergson's  position  is  illustrated — and  what  is  to  be 
said  in  criticism  may  also  be  aptly  illustrated — by  Zeno's 
argument  of  the  arrow.  Zeno  argues  that,  since  the  arrow 
at  each  moment  simply  is  where  it  is,  therefore  the  arrow 
in  its  flight  is  always  at  rest.  At  first  sight,  this  argument 
may  not  appear  a  very  powerful  one.  Of  course,  it  will  be 
said,  the  arrow  is  where  it  is  at  one  moment,  but  at  another 
moment  it  is  somewhere  else,  and  this  is  just  what  con- 
stitutes motion.  Certain  difficulties,  it  is  true,  arise  out  of 
the  continuity  of  motion,  if  we  insist  upon  assuming  that 
motion  is  also  discontinuous.  These  difficulties,  thus  ob- 
tained, have  long  been  part  of  the  stock-in-trade  of  phi- 
losophers. But  if,  with  the  mathematicians,  we  avoid  the 
assumption  that  motion  is  also  discontinuous,  we  shall  not 
fall  into  the  philosopher's  difficulties.  A  cinematograph  in 
which  there  are  an  infinite  number  of  films,  and  in  which 
there  is  never  a  next  film  because  an  infinite  number  come 
between  any  two,  will  perfectly  represent  a  continuous  mo- 
tion. Wherein,  then,  lies  the  force  of  Zeno's  argument? 

Zeno  belonged  to  the  Eleatic  school,  whose  object  was 
to  prove  that  there  could  be  no  such  thing  as  change.  The 
natural  view  to  take  of  the  world  is  that  there  are  things 
which  change ;  for  example,  there  is  an  arrow  which  is  now 
here,  now  there.  By  bisection  of  this  view,  philosophers 
have  developed  two  paradoxes.  The  Eleatics  said  that 
there  were  things  but  no  changes ;  Heraclitus  and  Bergson 
said  that  there  were  changes  but  no  things.  The  Eleatics 
said  there  was  an  arrow,  but  no  flight;  Heraclitus  and 
Bergson  said  there  was  a  flight  but  no  arrow.  Each  party 
conducted  its  argument  by  refutation  of  the  other  party. 
How  ridiculous  to  say  there  is  no  arrow !  say  the  "static" 
party.  How  ridiculous  to  say  there  is  no  flight!  say  the 


34O  THE  MONIST. 

"dynamic"  party.  The  unfortunate  man  who  stands  in  the 
middle  and  maintains  that  there  is  both  the  arrow  and  its 
flight  is  assumed  by  the  disputants  to  deny  both;  he  is 
therefore  pierced,  like  St.  Sebastian,  by  the  arrow  from 
one  side  and  by  its  flight  from  the  other.  But  we  have  still 
not  discovered  wherein  lies  the  force  of  Zeno's  argument. 

Zeno  assumes,  tacitly,  the  essence  of  the  Bergsonian 
theory  of  change.  That  is  to  say,  he  assumes  that  when  a 
thing  is  in  a  process  of  continuous  change,  even  if  it  is 
only  change  of  position,  there  must  be  in  the  thing  some 
internal  state  of  change.  The  thing  must,  at  each  instant, 
be  intrinsically  different  from  what  it  would  be  if  it  were 
not  changing.  He  then  points  out  that  at  each  instant  the 
arrow  simply  is  where  it  is,  just  as  it  would  be  if  it  were  at 
rest.  Hence  he  concludes  that  there  can  be  no  such  thing 
as  a  state  of  motion,  and  therefore,  adhering  to  the  view 
that  a  state  of  motion  is  essential  to  motion,  he  infers  that 
there  can  be  no  motion  and  that  the  arrow  is  always  at  rest. 

Zeno's  argument,  therefore,  though  it  does  not  touch 
the  mathematical  account  of  change,  does,  prima  facie, 
refute  a  view  of  change  which  is  not  unlike  M.  Bergson's. 
How,  then,  does  M.  Bergson  meet  Zeno's  argument?  He 
meets  it  by  denying  that  the  arrow  is  ever  anywhere.  After 
stating  Zeno's  argument,  he  replies:  "Yes,  if  we  suppose 
that  the  arrow  can  ever  be  in  a  point  of  its  course.  Yes 
again,  if  the  arrow,  which  is  moving,  ever  coincides  with  a 
position,  which  is  motionless.  But  the  arrow  never  is  in 
any  point  of  its  course"  (C.  E..,  p.  325).  This  reply  to 
Zeno,  or  a  closely  similar  one  concerning  Achilles  and  the 
Tortoise,  occurs  in  all  his  three  books.  Bergson's  view, 
plainly,  is  paradoxical;  whether  it  is  possible,  is  a  ques- 
tion which  demands  a  discussion  of  his  view  of  duration. 
His  only  argument  in  its  favor  is  the  statement  that  the 
mathematical  view  of  change  "implies  the  absurd  propo- 
sition that  movement  is  made  of  immobilities"  (C.  E.,  p. 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON.  34! 

325).  But  the  apparent  absurdity  of  this  view  is  merely 
due  to  the  verbal  form  in  which  he  has  stated  it,  and  van- 
ishes as  soon  as  we  realize  that  motion  implies  relations. 
A  friendship,  for  example,  is  made  out  of  people  who  are 
friends,  but  not  out  of  friendships;  a  genealogy  is  made 
out  of  men,  but  not  out  of  genealogies.  So  a  motion  is 
made  out  of  what  is  moving,  but  not  out  of  motions.  It 
expresses  the  fact  that  a  thing  may  be  in  different  places  at 
different  times,  and  that  the  places  may  still  be  different 
however  near  together  the  times  may  be.  Bergson's  argu- 
ment against  the  mathematical  view  of  motion,  therefore, 
reduces  itself,  in  the  last  analysis,  to  a  mere  play  upon 
words.  And  with  this  conclusion  we  may  pass  on  to  a 
criticism  of  his  theory  of  duration. 

Bergson's  theory  of  duration  is  bound  up  with  his  the- 
ory of  memory.  According  to  this  theory,  things  remem- 
bered survive  in  memory,  and  thus  interpenetrate  present 
things :  past  and  present  are  not  mutually  external,  but  are 
mingled  in  the  unity  of  consciousness.  Action,  he  says,  is 
what  constitutes  being;  but  mathematical  time  is  a  mere 
passive  receptacle,  which  does  nothing  and  therefore  is 
nothing  (C.  E.,  p.  41).  The  past,  he  says,  is  that  which 
acts  no  longer,  and  the  present  is  that  which  is  acting  (M. 
and  M.,  p.  74).  But  in  this  statement,  as  indeed  through- 
out his  account  of  duration,  Bergson  is  unconsciously  as- 
suming the  ordinary  mathematical  time;  without  this,  his 
statements  are  unmeaning.  What  is  meant  by  saying  "the 
past  is  essentially  that  which  acts  no  longer"  (his  italics), 
except  that  the  past  is  that  of  which  the  action  is  past  ?  The 
words  "no  longer"  are  words  expressive  of  the  past;  to  a 
person  who  did  not  have  the  ordinary  notion  of  the  past  as 
something  outside  the  present,  these  words  would  have  no 
meaning.  Thus  his  definition  is  circular.  What  he  says  is, 
in  effect,  "the  past  is  that  of  which  the  action  is  in  the  past." 
As  a  definition,  this  cannot  be  regarded  as  a  happy  effort. 


342  THE  MONIST. 

And  the  same  applies  to  the  present.  The  present,  we  are 
told,  is  "that  which  is  acting"  (his  italics).3  But  the  word 
"is"  introduces  just  that  idea  of  the  present  which  was  to 
be  defined.  The  present  is  that  which  is  acting  as  opposed 
to  that  which  was  acting  or  will  be  acting.  That  is  to  say, 
the  present  is  that  whose  action  is  in  the  present,  not  in  the 
past  or  in  the  future.  Again  the  definition  is  circular.  An 
earlier  passage  on  the  same  page  will  illustrate  the  fallacy 
further.  "That  which  constitutes  our  pure  perception,"  he 
says,  "is  our  dawning  action.  . .  .The  actuality  of  our  per- 
ception thus  lies  in  its  activity,  in  the  movements  which 
prolong  it,  and  not  in  its  greater  intensity :  the  past  is  only 
idea,  the  present  is  ideo-motor"  (ib.).  This  passage  makes 
it  quite  clear  that,  when  Bergson  speaks  of  the  past,  he 
does  not  mean  the  past,  but  our  present  memory  of  the  past. 
The  past  when  it  existed  was  just  as  active  as  the  present 
is  now;  if  Bergson's  account  were  correct,  the  present 
moment  ought  to  be  the  only  one  in  the  whole  history  of 
the  world  containing  any  activity. 

In  earlier  times  there  were  other  perceptions,  just  as  ac- 
tive, just  as  actual  in  their  day, as  our  present  perception; 
the  past,  in  its  day,  was  by  no  means  only  idea,  but  was  in  its 
intrinsic  character  just  what  the  present  is  now.  This  real 
past,  however,  Bergson  simply  forgets ;  what  he  speaks  of 
is  the  present  idea  of  the  past.  The  real  past  does  not 
mingle  with  the  present.  Our  memory  of  the  past  does 
of  course  mingle  with  the  present,  since  it  is  part  of  it ;  but 
that  is  a  very  different  thing. 

The  whole  of  Bergson's  theory  of  duration  and  time 
rests  throughout  on  the  elementary  confusion  between  the 
present  occurrence  of  a  recollection  and  the  past  occurrence 
which  is  recollected.  But  for  the  fact  that  time  is  so  f amil- 

*  Similarly  in  Matter  and  Memory  (p.  193)  he  says  it  is  a  question  whether 
the  past  has  ceased  to  exist,  or  has  only  ceased  to  be  useful.  The  present,  he 
says,  is  not  that  which  is,  but  that  which  is  being  made.  The  words  I  have 
italicized  here  really  involve  the  usual  view  of  time. 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON.  343 

iar  to  us,  the  vicious  circle  involved  in  his  attempt  to  deduce 
the  past  as  what  is  no  longer  active  would  be  obvious  at 
once.  As  it  is,  what  Bergson  gives  is  an  account  of  the 
difference  between  perception  and  recollection — both  pres- 
ent facts — and  what  he  believes  himself  to  have  given  is 
an  account  of  the  difference  between  the  present  and  the 
past.  As  soon  as  this  confusion  is  realized,  his  theory 
of  time  is  seen  to  be  simply  a  theory  which  omits  time  alto- 
gether. 

The  confusion  between  present  remembering  and  the 
past  event  remembered,  which  seems  to  be  at  the  bottom 
of  Bergson's  theory  of  time,  is  an  instance  of  a  more  gen- 
eral confusion  which,  if  I  am  not  mistaken,  vitiates  a  great 
deal  of  his  thought,  and  indeed  a  great  deal  of  the  thought 
of  most  modern  philosophers — I  mean  the  confusion  be- 
tween an  act  of  knowing  and  that  which  is  known.  In 
memory,  the  act  of  knowing  is  in  the  present,  whereas  what 
is  known  is  in  the  past;  thus  by  confusing  them  the  dis- 
tinction between  past  and  present  is  blurred.  In  percep- 
tion, the  act  of  knowing  is  mental,  whereas  what  is  known 
is  (at  least  in  one  sense)  physical  or  material;  thus  by  con- 
fusing the  two,  the  distinction  between  mind  and  matter  is 
blurred.  This  enables  Bergson  to  say,  as  we  saw,  that 
"pure  perception,  which  is  the  lowest  degree  of  mind. . .  .is 
really  part  of  matter/'  The  act  of  perceiving  is  mind, 
while  that  which  is  perceived  is  (in  one  sense)  matter; 
thus  when  these  two  are  confused,  the  above  statement 
becomes  intelligible. 

Throughout  Matter  and  Memory,  this  confusion  be- 
tween the  act  of  knowing  and  the  object  known  is  indis- 
pensable. It  is  enshrined  in  the  use  of  the  word  "image," 
which  is  explained  at  the  very  beginning  of  the  book.4 

4Bergson's  use  of  the  word  "image"  is  made  clearer  by  a  very  pene- 
trating analysis  of  Berkeley  in  a  recent  article,  "L'Intuition  Philosophique" 
(Revue  de  Metaphysique  et  de  Morale,  Nov.  1911).  This  article  displays  very 
distinctly  the  profound  influence  of  Berkeley  on  Bergson's  thought.  Berg- 
son's  "image"  is  practically  Berkeley's  "idea." 


344  THE  MONIST. 

He  there  states  that,  apart  from  philosophical  theories, 
everything  that  we  know  consists  of  "images,"  which  in- 
deed constitute  the  whole  universe.  He  says :  "I  call  mat- 
ter the  aggregate  of  images,  and  perception  of  matter  these 
same  images  referred  to  the  eventual  action  of  one  par- 
ticular image,  my  body"  (M.  and  M.,  p.  8).  It  will  be 
observed  that  matter  and  the  perception  of  matter,  accord- 
ing to  him,  consist  of  the  very  same  things.  The  brain,  he 
says,  is  like  the  rest  of  the  material  universe,  and  is  there- 
fore an  image  if  the  universe  is  an  image  (p.  9). 

Since  the  brain,  which  nobody  sees,  is  not,  in  the  ordi- 
nary sense,  an  image,  we  are  not  surprised  at  his  saying 
that  an  image  can  be  without  being  perceived  (p.  27)  ;  but 
he  explains  later  on  that,  as  regards  images,  the  difference 
between  being  and  being  consciously  perceived  is  only  one 
of  degree  (p.  30).  This  is  perhaps  explained  by  another 
passage  in  which  he  says:  "What  can  be  a  non-perceived 
material  object,  an  image  not  imaged,  unless  it  is  a  kind 
of  unconscious  mental  state?"  (p.  183).  Finally  (p.  304) 
he  says :  "That  every  reality  has  a  kinship,  an  analogy,  in 
short  a  relation  with  consciousness — this  is  what  we  con- 
cede to  idealism  by  the  very  fact  that  we  term  things  'im- 
ages.' '  Nevertheless  he  attempts  to  allay  our  initial  doubt 
by  saying  that  he  is  beginning  at  a  point  before  any  of  the 
assumptions  of  philosophers  have  been  introduced.  "We 
will  assume,"  he  says,  "for  the  moment  that  we  know 
nothing  of  theories  of  matter  and  theories  of  spirit,  nothing 
of  the  discussions  as  to  the  reality  or  ideality  of  the  external 
world.  Here  I  am  in  the  presence  of  images"  (p.  i ).  And 
in  the  new  Introduction  which  he  wrote  for  the  English 
edition  he  says :  "By  'image'  we  mean  a  certain  existence 
which  is  more  than  that  which  the  idealist  calls  a  represen- 
tation, but  less  than  that  which  the  realist  calls  a  thing, — 
an  existence  placed  halfway  between  the  'thing'  and  the 
'representation'"  (p.  vii). 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON.  345 

The  distinction  which  Bergson  has  in  mind  in  the  above 
is  not,  I  think,  the  distinction  between  the  imaging  as  a 
mental  occurrence  and  the  thing  imaged  as  an  object.  He 
is  thinking  of  the  distinction  between  the  thing  as  it  is  and 
the  thing  as  it  appears,  neither  of  which  belongs  to  the 
subject.  The  distinction  between  subject  and  object,  be- 
tween the  mind  which  thinks  and  remembers  and  has  im- 
ages on  the  one  hand,  and  the  objects  thought  about,  re- 
membered, or  imaged — this  distinction,  so  far  as  I  can 
see,  is  wholly  absent  from  his  philosophy.  Its  absence  is 
his  real  debt  to  idealism ;  and  a  very  unfortunate  debt  it  is. 
In  the  case  of  "images,"  as  we  have  just  seen,  it  enables 
him  first  to  speak  of  images  as  neutral  between  mind  and 
matter,  then  to  assert  that  the  brain  is  an  image  in  spite  of 
the  fact  that  it  has  never  been  imaged,  then  to  suggest  that 
matter  and  the  perception  of  matter  are  the  same  thing, 
but  that  a  non-perceived  image  (such  as  the  brain)  is  an 
unconscious  mental  state ;  while  finally,  the  use  of  the  word 
"image,"  though  involving  no  metaphysical  theories  what- 
ever, nevertheless  implies  that  every  reality  has  "a  kin- 
ship, an  analogy,  in  short  a  relation"  with  consciousness. 

All  these  confusions  are  due  to  the  initial  confusion  of 
subject  and  object.  The  subject — a  thought  or  an  image 
or  a  memory — is  a  present  fact  in  me;  the  object  may  be 
the  law  of  gravitation  or  my  friend  Jones  or  the  old  Cam- 
panile of  Venice.  The  subject  is  mental  and  is  here  and 
now.  Therefore,  if  subject  and  object  are  one,  the  object 
is  mental  and  is  here  and  now ;  my  friend  Jones,  though  he 
believes  himself  to  be  in  South  America  and  to  exist  on  his 
own  account,  is  really  in  my  head  and  exists  in  virtue  of 
my  thinking  about  him;  St.  Mark's  Campanile,  in  spite  of 
its  great  size  and  the  fact  that  it  ceased  to  exist  ten  years 
ago,  still  exists,  and  is  to  be  found  complete  inside  me. 
These  statements  are  no  travesty  of  Bergson's  theories  of 


346  THE  MONIST. 

space  and  time ;  they  are  merely  an  attempt  to  show  what 
is  the  actual  concrete  meaning  of  those  theories. 

The  confusion  of  subject  and  object  is  not  peculiar  to 
Bergson,  but  is  common  to  many  idealists  and  many  mate- 
rialists. Many  idealists  say  that  the  object  is  really  the 
subject,  and  many  materialists  say  that  the  subject  is  really 
the  object.  They  agree  in  thinking  these  two  statements 
very  different,  while  yet  holding  that  subject  and  object  are 
not  different.  In  this  respect,  we  may  admit,  Bergson  has 
merit,  for  he  is  as  ready  impartially  to  identify  subject  with 
object  as  to  identify  object  with  subject.  As  soon  as  this 
identification  is  rejected,  his  whole  system  collapses:  first 
his  theories  of  space  and  time,  then  his  belief  in  real  con- 
tingency, then  his  condemnation  of  intellect,  then  his  ac- 
count of  the  relations  of  mind  and  matter,  and  last  of  all 
his  whole  view  that  the  universe  contains  no  things,  but 
only  actions,  movements,,  changes,  from  nothing  to  nothing, 
in  an  endless  alternation  of  up  and  down. 

Of  course  a  large  part  of  Bergson's  philosophy,  prob- 
ably the  part  to  which  most  of  its  popularity  is  due,  does 
not  depend  upon  argument,  and  cannot  be  upset  by  argu- 
ment. His  imaginative  picture  of  the  world,  regarded  as 
a  poetic  effort,  is  in  the  main  not  capable  of  either  proof  or 
disproof.  Shakespeare  says  life's  but  a  walking  shadow, 
Shelley  says  it  is  like  a  dome  of  many-colored  glass,  Berg- 
son says  it  is  a  shell  which  bursts  into 'parts  that  are  again 
shells.  If  you  like  Bergson's  image  better,  it  is  just  as 
legitimate. 

The  good  which  Bergson  hopes  to  see  realized  in  the 
world  is  action  for  the  sake  of  action.  All  pure  contempla- 
tion he  calls  "dreaming,"  and  condemns  by  a  whole  series 
of  uncomplimentary  epithets:  static,  Platonic,  mathemat- 
ical, logical,  intellectual.  Those  who  desire  some  prevision 
of  the  end  which  action  is  to  achieve  are  told  that  an  end 
foreseen  would  be  nothing  new,  because  desire,  like  mem- 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON.  347 

ory,  is  identified  with  its  object.  Thus  we  are  condemned, 
in  action,  to  be  the  blind  slaves  of  instinct:  the  life-force 
pushes  us  on  from  behind,  restlessly  and  unceasingly. 
There  is  no  room  in  this  philosophy  for  the  moment  of 
contemplative  insight  when,  rising  above  the  animal  life, 
we  become  conscious  of  the  greater  ends  that  redeem  man 
from  the  life  of  the  brutes.  Those  to  whom  activity  with- 
out purpose  seems  a  sufficient  good  will  find  in  Bergson's 
books  a  pleasing  picture  of  the  universe.  But  those  to 
whom  action,  if  it  is  to  be  of  any  value,  must  be  inspired 
by  some  vision,  by  some  imaginative  foreshadowing  of  a 
world  less  painful,  less  unjust,  less  full  of  strife  than  the 
world  of  our  every-day  life,  those,  in  a  word,  whose  action 
is  built  on  contemplation,  will  find  in  this  philosophy  noth- 
ing of  what  they  seek,  and  will  not  regret  that  there  is  no 
reason  to  think  it  true. 

B.  RUSSELL. 
CAMBRIDGE,  ENGLAND. 


PSYCHOTHERAPIC  CULTS:1 

CHRISTIAN  SCIENCE;   MIND  CURE;  NEW  THOUGHT. 


most  noteworthy  religious  event  since  the  Refor- 
_L  mation  is  perhaps  the  appearance  in  the  United  States 
of  a  number  of  religious  movements  which  may  be  grouped 
together  under  the  designation  of  psychotherapic  cults. 
The  foremost  of  them  is  "Christian  Science,"  founded  by 
Mrs.  Mary  Baker  Eddy. 

I  hasten  to  add  that  the  value  of  these  cults  does  not, 
in  my  mind,  belong  to  their  "metaphysics/'  considered  as 
a  philosophical  system.  It  is  the  product  of  ignorant  and 
ill-trained  minds.  Much  of  it  defies  logic  and  offends  com- 
mon sense.  But  the  defects  which  in  the  eyes  of  many 
wholly  damn  these  movements  might  conceivably  be  re- 
moved, and  there  would  remain  important  elements  of  a 
new  religious  faith  acceptable  to  the  modern  world. 

I  shall  try  to  show  that  the  psychotherapic  movements 
in  their  essential  teaching  are  popularized  and  distorted 
formulations,  on  the  one  hand,  of  important  truths  re- 
garding the  "power  of  thought"  over  body  to  which  psy- 
chology has  recently  given  added  significance,  and,  on  the 
other,  of  a  non-theistic  philosophy  allied  to  the  absolute 
idealism  of  modern  metaphysics.  Although  they  distort 
contemporary  thought,  they  do  not  intend  to  oppose  it. 
They  wish  rather  to  build  upon  it. 

1A  discussion  of  other  contemporary  movements  will  be  found  in  the 
author's  book,  A  Psychological  Study  of  Religion:  Its  Origin,  Function  and 
Future,  Macmillan,  1912. 


PSYCHOTHERAPIC  CULTS.  349 

These  new  cults  are  forcible  reminders  of  the  fact  that 
belief  in  a  saving  power  is  a  condition  of  the  existence  of 
religion,  and  also  that  the  desire  for  deliverance  from 
moral  and  physical  miseries  and  for  the  realization  of  ideals 
continues  to  be  the  motive  of  religious  life,  just  as  it  was 
in  the  days  of  Gautama  the  Enlightener,  and  of  Jesus  the 
Healer. 


The  mind-cure  books  announce  "the  discovery  of  the 
might  of  truth  in  the  treatment  of  disease  as  well  as  of 
sin/'  "the  vital  law  of  true  life,  true  greatness,  power, 
and  happiness."  They  claim  to  be  "systems  of  transcen- 
dental medicine/'  or  of  "psychic  therapeutics."  They  pur- 
pose to  minister  to  those  who  "would  exchange  impotence 
for  power,  weakness  and  suffering  for  health  and  strength, 
pain  and  unrest  for  peace,  poverty  for  fulness  and  plenty." 
They  proclaim  "the  birthright  of  every  man  born  into  the 
world  to  be  physically  whole  and  mentally  happy."  Their 
claims  have  an  extravagant  sound,  but  no  more  so  than 
those  made  for  "faith"  by  the  New  Testament  writers  who 
declared  it  would  remove  mountains  and  secure  eternal 
blessedness  after  death.  Nothing  but  vital  experiences  could 
have  inspired  the  enthusiasm  and  the  assurance  with  which 
these  modern  zealots  proclaim  the  abounding  efficacy  of 
their  "truth." 

If  they  call  themselves  Christians,  it  is  not  in  the  tra- 
ditional sense.  Of  traditional  Christianity  they  speak  re- 
spectfully, but  they  want  a  new  dogmatics.  They  say, 
"The  time  for  thinkers  has  come.  Truth,  independent  of 
doctrines  and  time-honored  systems,  knocks  at  the  portal  of 
humanity."2  In  another  of  their  aggressive  little  books 
one  reads:  "Unrest  is  universal.  The  old  landmarks  are 
disappearing.  . .  .Creed  and  dogma  are  things  of  the  past; 

3  Mary  G.  Baker  Eddy,  Science  and  Health,  1908,  Preface. 


35O  THE  MONIST. 

religious    ceremonial    and    form   no  longer    interest    the 


masses."3 


The  impression  these  cults  have  produced  on  thought- 
ful religious  people  is  well  expressed  in  this  passage: 

"Renan  with  his  usual  intuition  declared  that  if  it  [the 
religion  of  the  future]  were  already  in  our  midst,  few  of 
us  would  know  it. 

"The  prediction  has  proved  true.  The  new  religious 
movement  Christian  Science  has  spoken  a  language  so  for- 
eign to  cultivated  ears,  its  interpretation  of  the  Bible  is  so 
false,  it  is  so  obviously  committed  to  errors,  illusions,  and 
aberrations  of  every  sort,  that  the  intelligent  have  been 
disposed  to  shrug  their  shoulders  in  contempt  and  to  ignore 
it.  And  yet  they  have  not  been  able  to  ignore  it  altogether. 
Every  once  in  a  while  this  curious  superstition  proves  its 
existence  with  unexpected  power.  We  see  a  hard-headed 
business  man  totally  devoid  of  religious  sentiment  undergo 
a  new  kind  of  conversion  which  leaves  him  as  devout  and 
ardent  as  a  Christian  of  the  first  century.  An  ailing  wife 
or  daughter  whom  no  physician  has  been  able  to  help, 
through  some  mysterious  means  is  restored  to  health  and 
happiness.  The  victim  of  an  enslaving  habit,  apparently 
with  very  little  effort  and  without  physical  means,  suffer- 
ings, or  relapse,  finds  himself  free.  We  enter  a  home  where 
the  new  belief  reigns  and  we  find  there  a  peace  to  which 
we  are  strangers. 

"All  over  the  country  solid  and  enduring  temples  are 
reared  by  grateful  hands  and  consecrated  to  the  ideal  and 
name  of  Mrs.  Eddy.  And  this  strange  phenomenon  has 
occurred  in  the  full  light  of  day,  at  the  end  of  the  nine- 
teenth and  at  the  beginning  of  the  twentieth  century,  and 
these  extraordinary  doctrines  have  propagated  themselves 
not  in  obscure  corners  of  the  earth,  among  an  illiterate  and 
fanatical  population,  but  in  the  chief  centers  of  American 

8  Charles  B.  Patterson,  A  New  Heaven  and  a  New  Earth,  Preface. 


PSYCHOTHERAPIC  CULTS.  351 

civilization.     Such  facts  may  well  cause  the  philosophical 
student  of  religion  to  reflect.4 

In  these  movements  is  restored  the  alliance  between  the 
art  of  healing  the  body  and  the  art  of  healing  the  soul, 
which  was  always  a  leading  characteristic  of  the  higher 
religions  during  their  period  of  greatest  vitality.  To  the 
masses  the  most  impressive  aspect  of  religions  has  always 
been  their  power  to  heal  the  body.  It  was  so  in  the  early 
ministry  of  Christ  and  during  the  first  Christian  centuries. 
It  is  so  now  with  these  psychotherapists.  And  this  revival 
acquires  great  significance  from  the  fact  that  it  can  now 
be  grounded  upon  the  deeper  understanding  of  the  inter- 
relation of  mind  and  body,  which  we  owe  to  modern  science. 

Speaking  of  the  "four  noble  truths"  of  Buddhism, 
(Satyani),  i.  e.,  the  four  axioms  or  certainties :  the  existence 
of  suffering,  the  origin  of  suffering,  the  emancipation  from 
suffering  and  the  path  that  leads  to  the  emancipation  from 
suffering,  Kern  says:  "It  is  not  difficult  to  see  that  these 
four  Satyas  are  nothing  else  but  the  four  cardinal  articles 
of  Indian  medical  science,  applied  to  the  spiritual  healing 
of  mankind,  exactly  as  in  the  Yoga  doctrine.  This  con- 
nection of  the  Aryasatyas  with  medical  science  was  appar- 
ently not  unknown  to  the  Buddhists  themselves/'  And 
concerning  the  twelvefold  causal  root  of  the  evil  of  the 
world,  the  twelve  Nidanas  (causes),  he  declares  that  they 
stand  to  the  four  Satyas  'in  the  same  relation  as  pathology 
to  the  whole  system  of  medical  science/  Now  the  four 
truths  and  the  twelve  causes  are  fundamental  facts  upon 
which  Gautama's  scheme  of  deliverance  is  built/'5 

#       #       # 

My  chief  effort  will  be  to  get  from  the  writings  of  the 
leaders  of  these  therapeutic  schools  a  clear  idea  of  the 

*Elwood  Worcester,  Samuel  McComb,  Isador  H.  Coriat,  Religion  and 
Medicine,  New  York,  1908,  pp.  8-10. 

B  Kern,  Manual  of  Buddhism,  Grundriss  der  indo-arischen  Philologie  und 
Altertumskunde,  Vol.  Ill,  No.  8,  pp.  46-47. 


352  THE  MONIST. 

power  with  which  they  expect  to  regenerate  humanity,  and 
then  to  consider  its  adequacy.  Whatever  their  affiliations, 
these  writers  practically  agree  on  the  points  that  most 
interest  us.  I  do  not  shrink  from  putting  before  my  read- 
ers, to  begin  with,  brief  quotations  from  two  of  the  most 
extravagant  and  crude  of  these  authors ;  for  even  they  find 
followers  among  people  who  prove  themselves  intelligent 
and  sensible  in  the  affairs  of  life. 

T.  Troward,  a  leader  of  Mental  Science  (not  a  disciple 
of  Mrs.  Eddy),  late  divisional  judge  in  Punjab  and  Edin- 
burgh Lecturer  on  Mental  Science,  teaches  the  existence 
of  an  unlimited,  impersonal,  though  intelligent  power, 
which  man  may  press  into  service,  or  appropriate  to  him- 
self. His  view  of  man's  relation  to  that  power  is  curious. 
The  individual  can  call  it  into  action  and  give  it  direction, 
"because  it  is  in  itself  impersonal  though  intelligent."  "It 
will  receive  the  impress  of  his  personality,  and  can  there- 
fore make  its  influence  felt  far  beyond  the  limits  which 
bound  the  individual's  objective  perception  of  the  circum- 
stances with  which  he  has  to  deal.  It  is  for  this  reason 
that  I  lay  so  much  stress  on  the  combination  of  two  appar- 
ent opposites  in  the  Universal  Mind,  the  union  of  intelli- 
gence with  impersonality.  . .  .How  do  we  know  what  the 
intention  of  the  Universal  Mind  may  be?  Here  comes  in 
the  element  of  impersonality.  It  has  no  intention,  because 

it  is  impersonal Combining,  then,  these  two  aspects 

of  the  Universal  Mind, ....  we  find  precisely  the  sort  of 
natural  force  we  are  in  want  of,  something  which  will 
undertake  whatever  we  put  into  its  hands  without  asking 
questions  or  bargaining  for  terms,  and  which,  having 
undertaken  our  business,  will  bring  to  bear  on  it  an  intelli- 
gence to  which  the  united  knowledge  of  the  whole  human 
race  is  as  nothing,  and  a  power  equal  to  this  intelligence."6 

6T.  Troward,  The  Edinburgh  Lectures  on  Mental  Science,  The  Arcane 
Book  Concern,  1909,  Chicago,  pp.  66-68. 


PSYCHOTHERAPIC  CULTS.  353 

I  find  it  difficult  to  conceive  an  unlimited  impersonal 
intelligence  which  has  no  intention  and  which  individual 
intelligence  may  direct.  But  in  fairness  to  the  abstruse 
judge,  I  must  add  that  this  difficulty  is  no  greater  than  that 
presented  by  Hegel's  conception  of  the  Absolute  Mind. 

In  the  work  of  W.  F.  Evans  we  meet  a  consistent  pan- 
theism. He  strives  to  give  to  his  opinions  an  impressive 
background  compounded  of  modern  science,  antique  pan- 
theism, and  modern  idealism.  How  vast  and  accurate  is 
his  knowledge  will  appear  in  the  following  passage.  I 
quote  it  without  apology  as  another  instance  of  a  type  of 
conception  apparently  rational  enough  to  be  accepted  by 
many  intelligent  people.  "The  soul  of  man  is  a  part,  so 
to  speak,  of  the  anima  mundi,  the  soul  of  the  world."  The 
power  of  the  healing  thought  "issues  from  the  spiritual 
world  of  which  our  minds  are  a  part,  for  all  ideas  belong 
to  that  boundless  realm  of  life."  "It  is  stored  up  in  ex- 
haustless  and  overflowing  abundance  in  the  bosom  of  na- 
ture. . .  .it  can  be  controlled  in  its  lower  degrees  of  mani- 
festation by  the  intelligent  will  of  man,  which  is  the  highest 
form  of  its  development  and  expression."  "This  grand 
whole ....  the  universal  world  of  spiritual  intelligence  is 
called  in  Sanskrit,  Addi-Budda.  In  the  writings  of  Paul 
it  is  called  the  Christ.  . .  .It  is  identical  with  what  is  called 
magnetism,  and  is  also  that  which  the  philosophers  have 
called  the  divine  nous."1 

One  of  the  ablest  and  sanest  writers  of  New  Thought, 
Ralph  Waldo  Trine,  in  a  book  which  has  passed  its  seventy- 
fifth  thousand,  also  announces  a  pantheistic  gospel  of  an 
infinite  power  at  the  service  of  man.  "The  great  central 
fact  of  the  universe  is  that  spirit  of  Infinite  Life  and  Power 
that  is  back  of  all,  that  animates  all,  that  manifests  itself 
in  and  through  all ;  that  self-existent  principle  of  life  from 

7W.  F.  Evans,  The  Primitive  Mind-Cure:  Elementary  Lessons  in  Chris- 
tian Philosophy  and  Transcendental  Medicine. 


354  THE  MONIST. 

which  all  has  come,  and  not  only  from  which  all  has  come, 
but  from  which  all  is  continually  coming." 

"This  Infinite  Power  is  creating,  working,  ruling 
through  the  agency  of  great  immutable  laws  and  forces 
that  run  through  all  the  universe,  that  surround  us  on 
every  side.  Every  act  of  our  every-day  lives  is  governed 
by  these  same  great  laws  and  forces." 

"In  a  sense  there  is  nothing  in  all  the  great  universe 
but  law."  But  the  presence  of  laws  indicates  a  force  back 
of  them.  "This  Spirit  of  Infinite  Life  and  Power  that  is 
back  of  all  is  what  I  call  God." 

"God,  then,  is  this  Infinite  Spirit  which  fills  all  the 
universe  with  Himself  alone,  so  that  all  is  from  Him  and  in 
Him,  and  there  is  nothing  that  is  outside.  .  .  .He  is.  .  .  .our 
very  life  itself."  "In  essence  the  life  of  God  and  the  life 
of  man  are  identically  the  same,  and  so  are  one.  They 
differ  not  in  essence,  in  quality ;  they  differ  in  degree." 

" ....  if  the  God-powers  are  without  limit,  does  it  not 
then  follow  that  the  only  limitations  man  has  are  the  limi- 
tations he  sets  to  himself,  by  virtue  of  not  knowing  him- 
self?" 

"The  great  central  fact  in  human  life,  in  your  life  and  in 
mine,  is  the  coming  into  a  conscious,  vital  realization  of  our 
oneness  with  this  Infinite  Life,  and  the  opening  of  ourselves 
to  this  divine  overflow"  This  means  simply  "that  we  are 
recognizing  our  true  identity,  that  we  are  bringing  our 
lives  into  harmony  with  the  same  great  laws  and  forces, 
and  so  opening  ourselves  to  the  same  great  inspirations 
as  have  all  the  prophets,  seers,  sages,  and  saviours  in  the 
world's  history,  all  men  of  truly  great  and  mighty  power. "s 
He  does  not  hesitate  to  use  the  term  "God-man." 

8  Ralph  Waldo  Trine,  In  Tune  with  the  Infinite  or  Fullness  of  Peace, 
Power,  and  Plenty,  Thomas  Y.  Crowell  and  Co.,  New  York,  pp.  11-20. 


PSYCHOTHERAPIC  CULTS.  355 

Christian  Science. 

It  seems  almost  incredible  that  one  professing  to  be  a 
Christian  should  teach  the  impersonality  of  the  divine  na- 
ture. And  yet  this  is  undoubtedly  what  Mrs.  Eddy  does, 
and  in  this  respect  she  agrees  with  those  from  whom  I 
have  just  quoted.  The  term  that  she  prefers  as  a  name 
for  the  Divine  Power  is  Principle.  As  synonyms  she  uses 
Life,  Truth,  Love,  God.  In  the  earlier  editions  of  Science 
and  Health,  it  is  written  that  God  "is  not  a  person,  God  is 
Principle."9  This  is  undoubtedly  the  standpoint  of  her  later 
writings  also.  But  in  them,  probably  because  of  the  pres- 
sure of  adverse  public  opinion,  she  insists  less  than  at  the 
beginning  of  her  career  upon  the  impersonality  of  Prin- 
ciple, and  the  word  "person"  appears  more  frequently. 
"Once  in  1898,  Mrs.  Eddy  hints  that  God  may  be  personal 
'if  the  term  personality,  as  applied  to  God,  means  infinite 
personality/  and  Mr.  Farlow  in  1907  assures  the  Rev. 
Edgar  P.  Hill  that  Mrs.  Eddy  does  believe  that  'God  is  per- 
son in  the  infinite  sense.' '  '  I  take  the  following  passages 
from  the  same  book:  "Principle  in  her  theology  gathers 
up  into  itself  all  the  concepts  we  habitually  associate  with 
God,  except  the  most  important — personality.  Before  her 
book  appeared  in  1875,  she  was  telling  her  pupils,  as  two 
of  them  informed  me,  that  they  could  make  no  progress 
till  they  had  banished  from  their  minds  the  thought  of  God 
as  a  person.  She  instructed  Richard  Kennedy  'to  lay  spe- 
cial stress'  in  healing  patients  on  the  impersonality  of  God. 
This  is  the  commanding  thought  that  rings  through  the 
first  chapter  of  the  first  edition  of  Science  and  Health." 

"Mrs.  Eddy's  pantheism  is  unnecessary,  and  yet  its 
origin  was  inevitable  in  a  mind  as  literal  as  hers.  Quimby 
often  spoke  of  God  as  Principle.  In  the  Quimby  manu- 

9  Mary  G.  Baker  Eddy,  op.  cit.,  3d  ed.,  1881,  I,  67 ;  II,  27. 
10Lyman  P.  Powell,  Christian  Science,  the  Faith  and  its  Founder,  pp. 
139-140. 


356  THE  MONIST. 

script  from  which,  for  several  years,  Mrs.  Eddy  taught, 
no  sentence  is  more  startling  than  the  sentence  'God  is 
Principle/  " 

"For  more  than  thirty  years  Mrs.  Eddy  has  been  sol- 
emnly asserting  that  in  1866  she  received  a  'final  revelation/ 
Now  this  'final  revelation/  which  was  finally  as  well  as 
first  expressed  in  1875,  in  Science  and  Health,  is  saturated 
with  thought  that  God  is  not  a  person.  In  the  very  first 
chapter  we  are  informed  that  'God  is  Principle,  not  person/ 
[I  do  not  find  that  expression  in  the  first  chapter  of  the 
1908  edition,  but  it  is  in  No  and  Yes,  published  in  1909] 
that  Jesus  preached  the  impersonality  of  God,  that  the 
error  of  believing  in  the  personality  of  God  crucified  Jesus, 
that  the  trouble  with  conventional  Christianity  to-day  is 
that  it  makes  God  a  person.  ..  .'  (Pages  137-140). 

On  the  other  hand,  in  the  seventy-third  edition  of  No 
and  Yes,  published  in  1909,  a  pamphlet  intended  "to  cor- 
rect involuntary  as  well  as  voluntary  error,"  we  read :  "Is 
there  a  personal  Deity?  God  is  Infinite.  He  is  neither  a 
limited  mind  nor  a  limited  body.  God  is  Love ;  and  Love 
is  Principle,  not  person.  What  the  person  of  the  Infinite 
is,  we  know  not;  but  we  are  gratefully  and  lovingly  con- 
scious of  the  fatherliness  of  this  Supreme  Being.  God  is 
individual,  and  man  is  his  individualized  idea ....  Limitless 
personality  is  inconceivable ....  Of  God  as  person,  human 
reason,  imagination  and  revelation  give  us  no  knowledge. 

"When  the  term  divine  Principle  is  used  to  signify 
Deity  it  may  seem  distant  and  cold,  until  better  appre- 
hended. This  Principle  is  Mind,  Substance,  Life,  Truth, 
Love.  When  understood,  Principle  is  found  to  be  the  only 
term  that  fully  conveys  the  ideas  of  God, — one  Mind,  a 
perfect  Man,  and  divine  Science."11  This  Principle,  though 
not  a  person,  "is  intelligence." 

Although  she  wrote,  "God  is  All  in  all,"  and  "All  in  all 

11  Eddy,  No  and  Yes,  1909,  pp.  19,  20. 


PSYCHOTHERAPIC  CULTS.  357 

is  God,"12  she  will  not  be  called  a  pantheist.  In  the  edition 
of  No  and  Yes  already  quoted,  she  claims  that  "Christian 
Science  refutes  pantheism,  finds  Spirit  neither  in  matter 
nor  in  the  modes  of  mortal  mind.  It  shows  that  matter  and 
mortal  mind  have  neither  origin  nor  existence  in  the  eter- 
nal Mind.  . .  .For  God  to  know,  is  to  be;  that  is,  what  He 
knows  must  truly  and  eternally  exist.  If  He  knows  matter, 
and  Matter  cannot  exist  in  Mind,  then  mortality  and  dis- 
cord must  be  eternal."13 

Her  pantheism  is  in  any  case  not  materialistic,  since 
she  holds  matter  to  be  unreal,  a  deception  of  mortal  mind. 
Hers  is  an  idealistic  pantheism,  such  as  an  ignorant  person 
of  a  thoroughly  optimistic  temperament  might  evolve  on 
the  basis  of  imperfect  knowledge  of  absolute  idealism  and 
from  observation  of  the  mastery  of  mind  over  body. 

The  writings  of  Mrs.  Eddy's  disciples  reflect  the  un- 
critical, pantheistic  idealism  of  their  leader.  Their  favorite 
phrases  are  such  as  these:  "God's  presence  is  the  presence 
of  love;"  "God  is  life  everywhere  present;"  "One  life  fills 
all,  it  is  the  Perfect  Life." 

The  similarity  of  the  essential  aspects  of  New  Thought 
and  Christian  Science  to  the  mystical  element  in  Christian- 
ity is  evident.  Both  give  clear  expression  to  the  anti-isola- 
tion motive,  to  a  dynamic  belief  in  oneness-with-the-whole, 
and  both  feel  the  essence  of  the  cosmic  plasma  to  be  love. 
Man  is  steeped  in  all-embracing  Love.  He  need  only  place 
himself  in  unison  with  the  everlasting,  all-comprehending 
life-force  and  the  fulness  of  life  will  be  his.  How  love  can 
be  an  attribute  of  an  impersonal  power  does  not  seem  to 
give  Mrs.  Eddy  one  moment  of  uneasiness. 

In  their  curative  practices,  the  psychotherapic  cults 
have  the  benefit  of  the  recent  discoveries  concerning  the 
effects  of  suggestion.  Regarding  their  methods,  I  may 

"  Eddy,  Science  and  Health,  1898,  p.  7. 
13  Eddy,  No  and  Yes,  pp.  15,  16. 


358  THE  MONIST. 

say  here  merely  that  they  tend  to  place  the  person,  as  do 
the  practices  of  the  other  ethical  religions,  in  a  state  of 
increased  suggestibility,  a  state  described  in  part  by  the 
words  relaxedness,  collectedness,  monoideism,  meditation, 
communion.  This  condition  of  the  subject  aids  greatly  in 
the  realization  of  the  expected  benefits.  The  efficacy  of 
these  curative  methods  is  sufficiently  demonstrated  by  the 
wonderful  extension  of  the  movements.  In  every  walk 
of  life  people  bear  witness  to  the  saving  grace  that  is  in 
Christian  Science  or  in  New  Thought.  The  forces  of  a 
new  life  have  welled  up  within  them;  the  burdens  of 
existence  have  lightened,  nay,  have  disappeared ;  and  now 
they  walk  through  life  contented,  hopeful,  and  aggressively 
benevolent. 

The  following  is  an  example  of  what  people  find  in 
Christian  Science  apart  from  the  cure  of  disease : 

"I  accepted  Science  and  Health  without  expecting  it  to 
offer  more  than  a  human  theory  about  life, — even  the  name 
did  not  lead  me  to  expect  it  to  be  religious;  in  fact,  the 
chief  incentive  to  my  reading  it  at  that  time  was  the  great 
kindness  and  sincere  sympathy  evinced  by  my  friend,  who 

placed  a  copy  at  my  disposal I  started  timidly  at  first, 

and  prayerfully,  lest  it  should  be  misleading,  but  before 
I  had  gone  very  far  I  experienced  that  wonderful  spiritual 
quickening  which  is  so  often  spoken  of  in  our  meetings. 
I  wish  I  could  tell  exactly  what  the  experience  meant  to 
me,  the  wonderful  awakening  I  had ;  how  old  things  van- 
ished and  all  things  became  new. .  It  seemed  as  if  the  bur- 
dens, perplexities,  doubts,  and  fears  had  all  suddenly  rolled 
away;  as  if  the  sun  had  emerged  from  behind  the  clouds, 
and  everything  was  again  bright  and  beautiful. 

"And  what  a  feeling  of  strength,  hope,  and  courage 
came!  Those  old  troublesome  questions,  especially  the 
question  of  death,  were  explained,  and  I  felt  a  wonderful 
release  to  know  that  death  was  not  of  God.  I  read  and 


PSYCHOTHERAPIC  CULTS.  359 

reread  the  latter  part  of  the  chapter  on  Christian  Science 
Practice,  where  that  glorious  truth  is  explained ;  it  was  so 
beautiful,  so  natural,  and  so  true.  There  was  such  perfect 
joy  to  me  in  that  freedom,  that  I  used  to  declare  over  and 
over  again,  of  those  who  had  just  passed  from  us  (the 
members  of  our  home  circle),  'They  are  not  dead;'  and  so 
free  was  I  made  from  the  old  bondage,  that  never  since 
then  has  the  thought  of  that  change  affected  me  as  it  did 
before."14 

Unnecessary  importance  is  attached  by  the  critical  pub- 
lic to  the  vagaries  of  Christian  Science  and  of  New 
Thought;  for  instance,  to  the  denial  of  the  reality  of  mat- 
ter, and  therefore  of  disease;  to  the  wild  hopes  of  some  of 
their  prophets  that  "the  time  will  certainly  come  when  the 
highly  developed  man  will  have  the  power  to  lay  down  or 
take  up  his  life  through  a  conscious  knowlege  of  the  laws 
of  eternal  being  and  the  direct  application  of  these  laws 
to  his  own  life." 

When  I  say  "wild  hopes,"  I  speak  as  the  prosaic  man 
that  I  am.  No  less  a  philosopher  than  Bergson  has  ex- 
pressed that  same  hope  of  overcoming  death. 

An  apologist  of  the  psychotherapic  sects  would  be  justi- 
fied in  making  the  following  claims : 

1.  The  salvation  they  promise  is  first  of  all  for  this 
life. 

2.  The  soul  is  not  saved  independently  of  the  body.  The 
nefarious  asceticism  of  older  faiths  is  impossible  on  the 
principles  of  Christian  Science. 

3.  Their  ideal  involves  efficiency  in  the  conduct  of  this 
life. 

4.  Their  conception  of  salvation  is  free  from  anything 
miraculous.    They  dispense  with  the  wonders  of  the  Fall, 

14  Christian  Science  Sentinel,  Dec.  3,  1901. 
"Charles  B.  Patterson,  op.  tit.,  Preface. 


360  THE  MONIST. 

of  the  self-sacrifice  of  a  divine  personage,  and  of  salvation 
by  his  atonement. 

5.  They  divert  attention  from  the  sense  of  guilt  and 
suffering,  and  direct  it  to  an  immediately  accessible  healing 
and  invigorating  power. 

6.  Although  they  usually  define  the  aim  of  life  in  terms 
of  power,  happiness,  and  love,  they  cannot  fairly  be  charged 
either  with  insensitiveness  to  moral  values,  or  with  indiffer- 
ence to  the  ethical  advancement  of  mankind. 

7.  Despite  its  extravagance,  their  "metaphysics"  may 
be  regarded  as  a  formulation,  crude  and  distorted,  of  a 
Weltanschauung  made  unavoidable  by  modern  knowledge, 
—a  Weltanschauung,  opposed  in  several  important  respects 
to  the  traditional  but  no  longer  acceptable  Christian  philos- 
ophy. 

8.  These  cults  have  proved  their  value  by  their  results. 
In  estimating  the  chances  of  continued  life  of  religious 

movements,  one  should  bear  in  mind  that  vitally  beneficial 
beliefs  may  carry  a  heavy  load  of  error  and  even  of  ab- 
surdity. The  Christian  religion  was  not  destroyed  by  the 
expectation  of  the  second  coming  of  the  Lord  and  of  the 
end  of  the  world,  by  extravagant  notions  of  the  power  of 
faith,  by  absurd  or  incomprehensible  doctrines  regarding 
the  means  of  salvation,  the  resurrection  of  the  body,  and 
the  like.  There  is  enough  substantial,  practical  truth  in 
Christianity  to  bear  the  enormous  doctrinal  dead  weight 
it  carries  even  to  this  day.  It  may  be  possible  for  the  psy- 
chotherapic  doctrines  to  be  purified  in  a  reformation  which 
would  either  remove  entirely  or  drive  into  side-currents 
most  of  the  offensive  tenets. 

J.  H.  LEUBA. 
BRYN  MAWR  COLLEGE,  PA. 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE. 

A  POETIZATION  OF  'THE  HAKO"—  A  PAWNEE  CEREMONY. 

BY  HARTLEY  BURR  ALEXANDER. 

PREFATORY  NOTE.  The  22d  Annual  Report  of  the  Bureau  of  American 
Ethnology  contains  Alice  C.  Fletcher's  record  of  "The  Hako :  a  Pawnee  Cere- 
mony." This  record  is  the  foundation  of  the  present  work.  Miss  Fletcher,  in 
her  rhythmic  renderings  of  the  Indian  songs,  has  incorporated  meanings  given 
in  the  explanations  of  the  leader  of  the  ceremony  as  well  as  the  literal  sense 
of  the  Indian  texts ;  the  result  being  a  series  of  admirable  translations,  abound- 
ing in  telling  phrases.  The  version  here  presented  has  drawn  freely  upon  Miss 
Fletcher's  fine  renderings;  but  as  "The  Mystery"  was  designed  to  emphasize 
the  universal  elements  in  the  Indian  thought,  it  necessarily  involved  generali- 
zation and  amplification  of  the  primitive  expression,  as  well  as  rearrangement 
of  materials. — The  piece  was  conceived  as  a  dramatic  pageant,  with  musical 
accompaniment,  as  will  appear  from  its  form. 

DESCRIPTION  OF  THE  SYMBOLS. 
The  Persons: 

The  LEADER,  a  Priest.  He  wears  leggings  and  moccasins,  and  a  robe  girt 
about  his  body,  leaving  shoulders  and  arms  bare ;  in  his  hair  is  a  feather 
of  white  eagle's  down;  he  carries  the  brown-plumed  wand. 

Five  ACOLYTES,  dressed  like  the  Leader.  They  carry  the  ceremonial  articles 
and  act  as  assistants  to  the  Leader. 

The  CHORUS,  consisting  of 

(A)  The  SEMI-CHORUS  OF  FATHERS,  led  by  the  CHIEF  OF  THE  FATHERS.  They 
are  dressed  in  leggings  and  moccasins  and  ceremonial  shirts,  ornamented 
with  blue  and  white.    They  wear  bonnets  of  white  eagle's  plumes.    The 
Chief  carries  a  calumet  and  his  bonnet  extends  in  streamers  of  plumes 
down  his  back.    In  Part  II  the  bonnets  are  left  off,  and  all  wear  blan- 
kets, symbolic  of  night. 

(B)  The  SEMI-CHORUS  OF  THE  CHILDREN,  led  by  the  CHIEF  OF  THE  CHIL- 
DREN.   They  are  dressed  like  the  Fathers,  except  that  their  colors  are 
green  and  red  and  their  bonnets  adorned  with  brown  plumes.    In  Part 
II  they  also  leave  off  the  bonnets  and  wear  blankets. 


362  THE  MONIST. 

The  CHILD. 

The  PERSONATOR  OF  THE  MORNING- STAR,  dressed  in  red,  and  wearing  a  red 
plume;  spread  wings  are  attached  to  his  wrists. 

The  Powers : 
The  BLUE  SKY,  abode  of  the  FATHER  OF  HEAVEN,  the  Mighty  Power. 

The  POWERS  OF  HEAVEN:  The  MORNING  STAR,  Herald  of  Day;  the  DAWN, 
Child  of  Heaven  and  of  Night;  the  SUN,  Father  of  Day  and  of  Life; 
the  Four  WINDS  from  the  Four  Quarters  of  the  World,  where  are  the 
Paths  from  Earth  to  Heaven. 

MOTHER  EARTH,  whose  Child  is  the  Green  Vegetation  symbolized  by  the  CORN 
SPIRIT,  andfwho  sustains  life  with  the  running  Waters  which  are  the 
WATERS  OF  LIFE  and  symbolize  the  continuing  generations  of  Mankind. 

The  EAGLE.  Chief  of  the  Birds  who  are  the  Mediators  between  the  Mighty 
Power  and  Man;  Conductor  of  the  Visions,  dwelling  in  the  lower 
Heaven,  down  to  Man ;  Symbol  of  the  care  which  the  Father  of  Heaven 
has  for  his  Children, — the  brown  plumes  being  emblematic  of  the  Fe- 
male Eagle  in  her  care  for  her  nestlings,  the  white  plumes  of  the  pro- 
tecting Male  Eagle:  the  place  of  the  white  is  always  outermost. 

Emblems  and  Ceremonial  Articles: 

The  BROWN-PLUMED  WAND,  borne  by  the  Leader:  a  hollow  stem,  painted 
blue,  emblematic  of  the  Sky,  and  adorned  with  a  fan  of  the  brown 
plumes  of  the  Female  Eagle;  also,  with  a  Duck's  head  and  breast,  one 
end  of  the  stem  being  thrust  through  the  mandibles;  with  a  tuft  of 
Owl  feathers;  with  red  and  white  streamers,  emblematic  of  Sun  and 
Stars. 

The  WHITE-PLUMED  WAND,  borne  by  an  Acolyte:  like  the  preceding  except 
that  the  stem  is  green,  symbolic  of  Earth,  and  the  plumes  are  the  white 
plumes  of  the  Male  Eagle. 

The  SPREAD  WINGS  OF  AN  EAGLE,  mounted  like  the  wings  on  the  caduceus 
of  Mercury,  except  that  each  wing  is  on  a  detachable  staff  so  that  they 
can  be  held  separately,  simulating  flight,  or  conjoined,  forming  a  banner. 

The  CORN,  a  light  sheaf  of  maize  with  unhusked  ears,  symbolic  of  the  Corn 
Spirit  and  of  the  Vegetation  which  is  the  offspring  of  life-giving  Mother 
Earth. 

The  BOWL,  hewn  from  the  living  wood,  a  part  of  Earth's  green  covering,  and 
painted  blue  as  symbolizing  the  blue  Sky.  In  it  is  borne  water  from  a 
running  stream,  symbolic  of  the  vigor  and  strength  which  Earth  gives 
in  the  Waters  of  Life  and  of  the  continuance  of  life  in  the  on-flowing 
generations  of  men. 

A  tray  with  implements  for  Fire-making;  a  tray  with  ceremonial  Tobacco; 
a  tray  with  four  cups,  one  containing  red,  one  blue,  and  one  green 
paint,  and  one  with  oil  and  fat.  Trays  of  bread;  jugs  of  water;  turfs 
for  building  the  hearth-altar. 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  363 

The  Place : 

The  PLACE  is  a  sward  of  level  green  on  the  open  prairie.  Above  is  the  blue 
sky  with  a  few  fleecy  clouds.  At  the  Western  side  of  the  sward,  form- 
ing the  background,  is  a  hedge  of  greenery,  with  three  openings  or  gates. 

The  Northern  Gate  is  the  Gate  of  the  Fathers,— North  is  the  side  of  Night 
and  of  the  need  of  protection. 

The  Southern  Gate  is  the  Gate  of  the  Children,— the  South  is  the  Winter 
home  of  the  birds,  the  side  of  peace  and  of  plenty. 

The  Middle  Gate,  facing  the  Place  of  Sunrise,  is  the  Gate  of  the  Leader  and 
Acolytes.  It  opens  from  the  Holy  Place. 

Color  Symbolism : 

BLUE  symbolizes  the  abode  of  the  Powers  Above  and  of  the  Father  of  Heaven ; 
GREEN  symbolizes  the  Earth  and  life-giving  food;  RED  is  the  color  of 
Life,  of  the  life-blood  and  of  the  Morning  Star  who  is  herald  of  light 
and  life;  WHITE  symbolizes  Sunlight,  the  fleecy  Clouds  and  the  Winds, 
and  hence  the  breath  of  Heaven,  the  Breath  of  Life. 

PART  I.  THE  COMING  OF  THE  CORN. 
THEME  I. 

Orchestral  Prelude.  Enter  from  the  Central  Gate  the  Leader  and  Acolytes; 
from  the  North  Gate,  the  Fathers;  from  the  South  Gate,  the  Children. 
The  Acolytes  and  the  Chorus  remain  at  the  Rear;  the  Leader  advances 
to  the  Forefront. 

The  Leader  intones: 

I. 

Give  heed !    Give  heed ! 

Give  heed,  O  ye  People! 

Unto  the  Abode  of  Life  give  ye  heed, 

And  unto  the  Powers  thereof 

Let  your  hearts  be  turned  in  reverence .... 

ii. 

Lift  up  your  gaze! 
Unto  the  blue  and  doming  Skies 

Lift  up  your  gaze, — 
Where  dwelleth  the  Father  of  Heaven, 
Where  dwelleth  the  Father  of  Life, 
Yea,  from  everlasting  to  everlasting. 

Lift  up  your  gaze 
Unto  the  Father!.. 


364  THE  MONIST. 

In  the  Circle  of  the  Heavens  He  hath  set 

The  manifestations  of  His  glory, — 

The  bright  and  shining  Sun, 

Which  giveth  forth  the  Light  of  Day 

And  answereth  the  hymn  wherewith  His  creatures 

Waken  at  Morn, — 

In  the  Circle  of  the  Heavens  He  hath  established  the  Sun 

To  be  a  sign  of  His  presence  by  Day, 

And  the  quiet  Stars  hath  He  set  to  be  His  nightly  ministers , 

The  Four  Winds 

From  the  Four  Pathways  of  the  Skies, — 
East,  South,  North,  West,— 
Breathe  forth  His  Word  and  His  Life 
Throughout  the  Lodge  of  Heaven: 
Yea,  the  music  of  His  Word 
And  the  gladness  of  Life 
Breathe  they  forth 
Through  the  Four  Quarters  of  the  World .... 

Lift  up  your  gaze 
Unto  the  blue  and  doming  Skies ! .  . .  . 


in. 

Upon  the  Earth 
Let  your  thoughts  descend, — 

Our  Mother  Earth ! 

From  her  dark  and  fruitful  womb  ye  are  sprung, 
And  at  her  nourishing  bosom  ye  are  fed : 
She  is  the  Great  Mother 
Who  keepeth  us  in  life 
And  at  death  receiveth  us: 

Think  on  the  Mother! 

Her  garment  is  the  fair  and  flowing  green, 
The  verdure  of  the  hills  is  her  habiliment, 
Whence  they  that  move  obtain  their  strength 
And  the  Sons  of  Men  their  sustenance: 
Who  is  the  Giver  of  Food  unto  her  children. 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  365 

As  milk  streameth  from  the  breast, 
From  her  ancient  hills 
And  the  cool  depths  of  her  yearly  snows 
The  clear  and  living  Waters  are  poured  forth, 
To  be  for  her  children  their  drink  and  their  refreshing: 
Yea,  unto  them  that  thirst  She  giveth  the  Waters  of  Life. 
Think  on  the  Mother ! 

IV. 

Upon  the  Earth 

Let  your  thoughts  descend  in  reverent  heed : 
Let  them  be  lifted  up 

To  the  blue  and  doming  Skies ! 

Upon  Earth  and  upon  Heaven  let  your  thoughts  be  placed, 
For  they  are  the  Abode  of  Life  and  of  the  Powers  thereof. . . 

THEME  II. 
Roll  of  drums.    The  Chorus  advances  a  pace,  crying  in  unison : 

Look  down!    We  gaze  afar  on  your  dwelling! 
Ye  Mighty  Ones,  look  down! 

During  the  orchestral  development  that  follows,  the  Semi-Chorus  of  Fathers 
advances  to  the  center  of  the  sward  where  they  form  a  circle,  with  an 
opening  to  the  East  and  one  to  the  West,  thus  simulating  the  circular 
outline  of  the  walls  of  an  earth  lodge.  With  their  hands  they  indicate 
the  building  of  walls.  .During  this  action  they  chant:  . 

Ye  of  the  Winds,  behold  us! 
Ye  Thunder  gods,  behold  us! 
Wielders  of  Leven,  behold  us ! 
Bringers  of  Death,  behold  us ! 

Ye  of  the  Rains,  behold  us! 
Ye  of  the  Clouds  and  the  Soil ! 
Givers  of  Increase,  behold  us! 
Givers  of  Life,  behold  us! 

We  establish  here  a  dwelling, — 
A  Wall  of  Defense, 
A  House  of  Life, 
A  Place  that  is  Holy ! 


366  THE  MONIST. 

Full  Chorus: 

Look  down !    We  gaze  afar  on  your  dwelling ! 
Ye  Mighty  Ones,  look  down! 

Semi-Chorus  of  Children  advances,  from  the  Western  opening,  within  the 
circle — the  symbolic  lodge — formed  by  the  Fathers.  They  carry  turfs 
which  they  build  into  an  hearth-altar  at  the  center  of  the  circle  as  they 
file  past.  They  form  into  two  half  circles,  North  and  South,  within  the 
circle  of  the  Fathers.  During  the  action  they  chant: 

Spirits  of  Heaven,  behold  us! 

Spirits  of  Earth,  behold  us! 

Ye  Shining  Ones,  behold  us! 

Ye  Darkling  Ones,  behold  us! 

Ye  that  measure  out  the  ways  of  men .... 

Here  we  build  unto  you  an  Altar, 
Whereof  the  flame  is  the  prayer  of  man 
Ascending. . . . 

The  Leader  enters  the  encircled  space  from  the  Eastern  opening,  three  Aco- 
lytes bearing  fire-making  implements  enter  from  the  West.  At  the 
Altar  the  Leader  lays  a  fire  and  sends  up  a  pillar  of  smoke,  like  an 
Indian  signal  smoke.  The  music  is  the  music  of  fire  and  of  prayer. 
As  the  smoke  ascends — 

The  Chorus: 

See!     The  Pillar  of  Smoke  ascendetK 
Up  to  the  dome  of  Heaven 
Where  God  abideth 

The  Leader: 

As  riseth  the  smoke  of  the  Altar, 
So  the  spirit  of  man  upstriveth, 
So  the  cry  of  his  heart  upmounteth, 
Unto  the  deeps  of  the  Blue, 
Unto  the  Silence  of  God.  . 


The  Chorus: 


Speed  aloft! 

Bearing  our  supplication, 

Bearing  our  prayer! 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  367 


THEME  III. 

The  flutes  strike  in  with  the  clear  piercing  music  of  the  Eagle.    The  Leader 
gazes  into  the  Eastern  Sky.     He  raises  his  arm  impressively,  crying: 

Lo,  where  cometh  His  answer — 
The  Eagle  of  the  Chief  of  Heaven ! 

The  Chorus  circles  North  and  South,  bringing  their  faces  to  the  East,  and 
then,  during  continuous  circling  motion : 

Behold,  an  Eagle  now  is  circling,  widely  circling  above  us! 

Semi-Chorus  of  Children,  circling  to  the  South : 

As  the  mother-bird  circleth  her  nestlings,  careful  for  her 

chicks, 
She  circleth  us,  hovering.  . .  . 

Semi-Chorus  of  Fathers,  circling  to  the  North : 
She  is  the  Eagle  of  God! 
Of  Him  who  is  Father  of  Heaven, 
Who  ruleth  the  quartered  Earth, 
And  sendeth  His  Will  by  the  Eagle 
Over  the  windy  Pathways 
That  lead  from  Man  up  to  God .... 

Semi-Chorus  of  Children : 

She  is  the  Eagle  of  God ! 

The  sign  that  He  hath  sent  us 

That  we  are  in  His  eyes 

As  to  the  mother-bird  are  her  nestlings.  . . . 

Semi-Chorus  of  Fathers : 

She  is  the  Eagle  of  God! 
Whose  coming  is  sign  of  His  blessing, — 
Of  the  gift  of  Food  to  His  children, 
Of  the  gift  of  Life  to  His  children, 
As  the  mother-bird  home  circling 
Beareth  food  and  life  to  her  nestlings .... 

Full  Chorus: 

Helpless  are  we  as  are  nestlings, 

Naked  as  unfledged  eaglets 

Lone  in  their  storm-beaten  crag. . . . 


368  THE  MONIST. 

Semi-Chorus  of  Fathers : 

About  them  circleth  the  Eagle, 

Strong  to  protect,  ever  watchful, 

His  plumes  flashing  white  in  the  sunlight, — 

The  cloud-frothing  winds  are  his  coursers! 

Semi-Chorus  of  Children: 

Over  them  hovereth  the  Eagle, 
She  of  the  brown  brooding  pinions, 
Bearing  them  food  in  her  talons, — 
As  the  Father  of  Heaven  permitteth. 

Full  Chorus: 

We  men  are  as  naked  and  helpless 

As  the  storm-beaten  chicks  of  the  Eagle .... 

He  of  the  wide-encircling  Heavens  guardeth  us, 
And  the  Sun-Father  watcheth  over  us ; 
Mother  Earth  bareth  Her  bosom  unto  us, 
Her  bounty  is  our  daily  bread .... 

Amid  silence  the  Leader  and  the  Acolytes  retire  through  the  Center  Gate,  as 
into  an  Holy  of  Holies.  The  Chorus  remains  ranged  in  the  North  and 
South  Forefronts. 

THEME  IV. 

The  oboes  and  bassoons  strike  up  the  droning  music  of  the  Corn.  The  tivo 
Chiefs  step  forward. 

Chief  of  the  Fathers : 

Father,  have  pity  upon  our  weakness, 
Father,  have  pity  upon  our  hunger : 
We  men  are  as  infants  before  thee, 
We  men  are  as  helpless  children 
Weeping  for  food .... 

Chief  of  the  Children : 

Out  of  far  distant  days  soft-stepping, 
I  beheld  one  coming,  a  Spirit  coming, 
Coming  to  comfort  me .... 

In  the  tender  and  caressing  night 

I  beheld  my  comforter:  :.    -' 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  369 

Her  wings  dropped  the  dews  of  fragrance; 
With  the  softness  of  stars  was  her  body  beautiful ; 
In  her  breast  were  the  singing  voices  of  the  fields .... 

There  enter  from  the  North  Gate  two  Acolytes,  one  bearing  a  tray  of  bread, 
one  bearing  a  jug  of  water,  and  from  the  South  Gate  two,  with  bread 
and  water.  The  Acolytes  with  the  bread  offer  the  bread  to  the  Fathers 
and  to  the  Children. 

Chief  of  the  Fathers: 

Lo,  they  bring  ye  the  Body  of  Mother  Earth : 
Take  thereof,  and  eat. 

While  they  partake  of  the  bread,  one  after  the  other,  the  Acolytes  with  the 
water  advance,  offering  the  water  to  the  Fathers  and  the  Children. 

Chief  of  the  Children: 

Lo,  they  bring  ye  the  Waters  of  Life : 
Drink,  and  be  refreshed. 

The  Fathers  and  the  Children  moisten  their  lips  as  the  water  is  offered  them. 
The  Acolytes  pass  forth  as  they  entered. 

The  music  becomes  tense,  vibrant  and  rapid.  The  Chorus  sways  to  and  fro 
in  a  crescendic  rhythm. 

From  the  Center  Gate  enter:  Two  Acolytes  each  bearing  a  staff  with  a  spread 
eagle-iving  attached;  the  Leader  and  an  Acolyte  bearing  the  plumed 
wands;  an  Acolyte  bearing  aloft  the  sheaf  of  maize;  an  Acolyte  with 
the  bowl.  They  range  themselves,  the  Leader  a  little  in  advance  and  to 
the  South,  the  Acolytes  abreast,  the  wings  at  the  ends,  the  Corn  in  the 
center,  the  white-plumed  wand  at  the  left  hand  of  the  Corn-bearer,  the 
bowl  at  his  right  hand. 

The  Chorus,  in  animated  motion,  bursts  forth  in  a  lyric  Hymn  to  the  Corn : 

Daughter  of  Heaven,  Earth's  first-born, 
Hail  to  thee!    Hail  to  thee!    Spirit  of  Corn! 
Thou  at  whose  bounteous  feasts  we  are  fed, 
Who  givest  us  life  in  giving  us  bread: 
Hail  to  thee !     Hail  to  thee !     Spirit  of  Corn ! 

Thou  who  dost  welcome  the  Sun-Father's  glance 
With  tassel  and  spear  flung  aloft  to  His  Morn, 
With  nodding  of  plume  and  waving  of  lance, 
Thou  who  dost  make  the  green  gardens  to  dance 
With  joy  of  thee,  joy  of  thee,  Spirit  of  Corn! 


37O  THE  MONIST. 

Thou  who  dost  gather  the  sunlight  and  rain 
Till  the  body  of  Earth  with  Heaven  is  o'erlain, — 
Life,  life  is  thy  largess,  who  givest  us  grain! 
Daughter  of  Heaven,  Earth's  first-born, 
Hail  to  the  thee !     Hail  to  thee !     Spirit  of  Corn ! 

They  cease  with  nodding  plumes. 


THEME  V. 

The  grave  music  of  the  Way  of  Life  enters  as  an  undertone  to  the  Corn  music. 
The  Leader  advances  to  the  Altar.  He  signals  to  the  Acolytes,  who  up- 
lift the  emblems.  He  addresses  the  Powers: 

Behold  us,  where  we  are  standing, 

Uplifting  these  emblems, — 

Ye  Mighty  Ones,  behold  us ! .... 

Out  of  the  Heavens,  cometh  a  flash! 

Out  of  the  Heavens,  the  light  of  His  seeing  eye! 

At  a  sign  the  five  Acolytes,  abreast,  advance  to  the  Altar,  before  the  Leader. 
They  present  the  emblems  to  the  East,  crying: 

Ye  of  the  East,  behold  us ! 
Ye  of  the  Dawn  and  the  Day! 

They  advance  sixteen  paces,  wheel,  and  elevate  the  emblems  to  the  West, 
crying : 

Ye  of  the  West,  behold  us! 

Ye  of  the  Storm  and  the  Night! 

They  return  sixteen  paces,  wheel  to  the  left,  advance  eight  paces  south,  and 
elevate  the  emblems  to  the  South: 

Ye  of  the  South,  behold  us! 
Ye  of  the  Path  of  the  Sun ! 

They  wheel  and  advance  sixteen  paces  to  the  North,  elevating  the  emblems  to 
the  North : 

Ye  of  the  North,  behold  us ! 
Ye  of  the  Mother  of  Day ! 

They  return  eight  paces  to  their  original  station  before  the  Altar,  and  once 
more  advance  sixteen  paces  to  the  East.  There  they  remain,  abreast. 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  371 

The  Leader  advances  eight  paces  from  the  Altar,  till  he  stands,  as  it  were, 
upon  the  heart  of  the  human  figure  traced  by  the  evolutions  of  the 
Acolytes. 

The  Leader: 

Ye  of  Heaven  and  Earth,  behold  us! 
Ye  Powers  of  Life,  behold  us ! .... 
Who  journey  the  way  of  man. 

Ye  have  given  us  for  our  Strengthener,  the  Spirit  of  Corn : 
Ye  have  given  us  for  our  Leader,  the  Spirit  of  Corn ! . . . . 
Who  journey  the  toilsome  way. 

As  the  Spirit  draweth  nigh,  we  bow  our  heads: 
As  the  Spirit  toucheth  us,  we  bow  our  heads .... 
Who  journey  the  Way  of  Life. 

While  the  music  grows  in  depth  and  gravity,  the  Chorus  moves,  forming  in 
a  phalanx  behind  the  Leader. 

Then  the  Chorus-. 

Open  our  way,  Spirit  of  Corn! 
Open  our  way,  Leader  in  Life ! 

The  Leader: 

Open  is  the  Way! 

We  are  led  as  were  our  fathers  led 

Down  through  the  ages: 

We  follow  as  they  did  follow. 

The  Leader  signals;  the  Chorus  moves  forward;  the  Acolytes,  abreast,  with 
the  emblems  upraised,  the  Corn  still  at  the  center,  lead  the  processional, 
which  circles  the  sward  and  finally  retires,  the  Leader  and  Acolytes 
through  the  Center  Gate,  the  Fathers  through  the  North,  the  Children 
through  the  South.  During  this  movement,  in  full  choral,  is  sung  the 
Chant  of  the  Way  of  Life. 

I. 

During  the  advance: 

Follow  on,  O  Brothers,  follow  on! 
The  Spirit  of  the  Corn  doth  lead 
And  unto  you  at  your  need 

Falleth  her  benison: 
Follow  on,  O  Brothers,  follow  on. 
Whither  your  sires  are  gone .... 


372  THE  MONIST. 

Your  feet  one  rhythm  beating, 
Your  tongues  one  song  repeating, 
Your  hearts  one  boon  entreating, 

Follow  ye  on! 
Forth  of  the  ruddy  Morn, 

Into  the  glowing  Day, 
Where  the  Spirit  of  the  Corn 

Showeth  the  way : 
Follow  on,  O  Brothers,  follow  on, 

Whither  your  sires  are  gone. 

ii. 

Circling  East: 

Lo.  the  Circle  of  the  Earth 

Is  the  circle  of  Man's  domain, 
And  he  buildeth  his  puny  hearth 

In  the  midst  of  her  spreading  plain,- 
And  Morning  and  Noon  and  Night 
He  kindleth  his  tiny  light. 

Circling  North : 

Heaven  hath  a  myriad  stars, 

Heaven  hath  the  burning  Sun, 
The  Day  and  the  Night  are  their  bars, 
And  their  course  is  never  run : 
In  the  hour  where  it  began 
Dieth  light  in  the  lodge  of  man. 

Circling  West: 

Man  walketh  in  ways  unknown, 

From  the  darkening  East  to  the  West- 
As  a  fledgling  that  hath  flown 
Forth  from  the  Eagle's  nest 
To  journey  the  pathless  skies 
With  the  sun  of  Heaven  in  his  eyes. 

Circling  South : 

Man  bareth  his  head  to  the  rain, 

His  breast  to  the  storm  layeth  bare, 
And  he  stalketh  athwart  the  plain 
Blind  in  the  lightning's  glare; 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  373 

And  heavy  on  his  soul 

Falls  the  terrible  thunder's  roll. 


IV. 

Circling  East: 

As  an  infant  that  is  led 

Amid  the  paths  of  surprise 
By  the  hand  that  giveth  him  bread — 
The  hand  of  the  foolish  or  wise — 
So  is  a  man  in  Their  care 
Who  measure  the  ways  he  must  fare. 

Circling  North : 

The  herds  of  the  prairies  pass, 

At  the  will  of  the  South  and  the  North, 
On  the  trail  of  the  greening  grass, 

Where  the  Spirit  of  Life  floweth  forth,- 
So  man  taketh  up  from  the  sod 
The  sacrament  of  God. 


v. 

Withdrawing : 

Follow  on,  O  Brothers,  follow  on! 
In  the  ways  whereto  ye  were  born, 
While  leadeth  the  Spirit  of  Corn 

Granting  her  benison: 
Follow  on,  O  Brothers,  follow  on, 

Whither  your  sires  are  gone ! . . . 
Your  feet  one  spirit  guiding, 
Your  lives  one  fate  abiding, 
In  the  wisdom  of  One  confiding, 

Follow  ye  on! 
Into  the  sombre  Night, 

Forth  of  the  flashing  Day, 
To  lands  beyond  your  sight 

Lieth  the  Way 

Follow  on,  O  Brothers,  follow  on, 

Whither  your  sires  are  gone. 

[Exeunt  omnes.] 


374  THE  MONIST. 


PART  II.   THE  REVELATION. 

THEME  VI. 

The  music  opens  with  an  eerie  prelude,  full  of  whispering  notes  suggestive  of 
things  supernatural  The  Chorus,  as  yet  unseen,  strike  in  with  their  In- 
vocation to  the  Visions.  They  enter  singing,  the  Children  from  the 
South,  the  Fathers  from  the  North.  They  wear  no  bonnets  and  they 
are  girt  with  blankets,  symbolic  of  Night.  They  circle  in  opposite  direc- 
tions, passing  and  repassing,  file  by  file. 

The  Chorus: 

Holy  Visions,  hither  come! 
Ye  who  dwell  in  rainbow  Skies 
Hidden  from  our  mortal  eyes 
By  the  lights  of  Paradise, — 

Holy  Visions,  hither  come! 

Holy  Visions,  hither  come! 
To  our  troubled  lives  descend, 
Draw  anigh  and  o'er  us  bend, 
That  our  hurts  may  have  an  end : 

Hither,  hither  come! 

Holy  Visions,  hither  come! 
If  we  wake  or  if  we  dream, 
Where  your  flashing  pinions  gleam 
There  doth  Heaven  on  us  beam: 

Holy  Visions,  come! 

Holy  Visions,  hither  come! 
Gift  of  joy  your  presence  brings,  • 
When  the  music  of  your  wings 
To  the  gladdened  spirit  sings: 

Hither,  hither  come! 

Holy  Visions,  hither  come! 
Glorified  the  spirit  blooms 
Where  the  splendor  of  your  plumes 
Like  a  sun  its  night  consumes: 

Holy  Visions,  come ! 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  375 

Holy  Visions,  hither  come! 
With  the  lightnings  of  your  glance 
Make  the  hearts  of  men  to  dance 
In  celestial  radiance: 

Hither,  hither  come! 

Holy  Visions,  hither  come! 
Bearing  with  you  Heaven's  Peace, 
Bearing  every  hurt's  release 
In  your  healing  mysteries : 

Holy  Visions,  hither  come! 

The  Chorus,  as  the  song  closes,  form  a  semi-circle  facing  eastward,  the 
Fathers  to  the  North,  Children  to  the  South.  They  kneel  and  draw 
their  robes  over  their  heads,  as  in  vigil  The  two  Chiefs  stand,  a  little 
in  advance. 

The  music  is  weird  and  mysterious,  with  innumerable  fluttering  crescendos, 
as  of  approaching  wings. 

Then  the  Chief  of  the  Fathers : 

Hark,  the  sound  of  their  wings ! 
Like  the  wings  of  mighty  eagles: 
Like  the  whistling  winds  on  the  prairies : 
Like  the  rushing  rain  on  the  corn ! . . . . 
Hark,  the  sound  of  their  wings! 

A  pause.    Then  the  Chief  of  the  Children: 

Was  it  in  dreams  that  our  Fathers  beheld  them? 
In  winged  dreams  that  they  came  revealing 
Unto  our  sires  the  Vision  of  Life? 

Chief  of  the  Fathers : 

Yea,  in  their  dreams  our  Fathers  beheld  them: 
In  shining  dreams  they  came  unveiling 
Unto  our  Sires  the  Vision  of  Life .... 

A  pause.    Then  the  Chief  of  the  Children: 

Hark,  the  sound  of  their  wings ! 
Mighty  spirits  hither  flying: 
Mighty  spirits  here  revealing 
Visions  as  in  days  of  yore. . . . 
Hark,  the  sound  of  their  wings! 

The  mysterious  music  continues  for  a  time;  then  dies  away  into  the  steady 
beating  of  deep-toned  drums.  An  utter  silence. 


376  THE  MONIST. 


THEME  VII. 

A  burst  of  drum-beats.  The  Chorus  throw  aside  their  robes  from  their  heads, 
and  rise,  crying: 

Awake,  O  Mother,  from  sleep !   The  night  is  far  spent. 
Awake,  O  Earth,  from  your  rest !  The  hills  and  the  valleys 

stir. 

Awake,  O  World,  from  your  night !  Day  summoneth  Earth 
and  Sky. 

The  Chorus  moves,  in  a  flowing  rhythm,  while  the  Chief  of  the  Children  sings 
the  Song  of  the  Dawning,  the  orchestra  sustaining  with  a  liquid  and 
lyric  mood: 

A  Wind  bloweth  forth  from  the  East, 

The  Wind  of  the  wakening  Dawn: 

The  clutches  of  Sleep  are  released 

Where  the  Wind  bloweth  on,  bloweth  on .... 

The  liquid  Wind  of  the  East, 

The  living  Breath  of  the  Dawn! 

Lo,  from  her  crag-built  nest 

The  Eagle  glanceth  afar! 

She  preeneth  her  golden  breast, 

And  with  sweep  of  her  pinions  doth  soar 

Over  the  world's  dim  crest 

Where  the  lights  of  the  Morning  are. 

See!     In  the  Eastern  sky, 

As  a  herald  that  runneth  swift, 

As  a  chieftain  who  draweth  nigh 

With  ruddy  plume  uplift, 

One  cometh  ....  and  passeth  by : 

The  tidings  of  Dawn  are  his  gift! 

Tis  the  Star  of  the  Morn,  of  the  Morn ! 

A  runner  whom  none  shall  withstay, 

Whose  red-shining  token  doth  warn, 

As  he  courseth  his  luminous  way, 

That  a  Child  from  the  Night  hath  been  born: 

The  Dawn!  who  foretelleth  the  Day! 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  377 

To  the  growing  animation  of  the  music,  the  Chief  of  the  Fathers'. 

Behold ! 
A  light  in  the  East! 

Behold ! 

The  whitening  Dawn! 
Unto  their  morning  feast 
The  creatures  of  light  move  on: 
In  pasture  and  brake 
The  world  is  awake 

With  browsing  herd  and  with  wilding  deer: 
The  Day  is  here! 

The  music  is  rapid  and  exultant.  The  Chorus  is  in  swift,  swinging  motion, 
with  imitative  action  suiting  the  words  of  their  choral.  All  about  is  an 
incessant  tinkling,  as  of  castanets  and  little  bells. 

The  Chorus-. 

Day  is  here! 

Day  is  here,  is  here,  is  here! 

Day  is  here,  is  here! 

Awake,  awake !    On  the  hills  the  light  is  breaking ! 
Awake,  awake !    The  heavens  are  aglow ! 
The  sleepers  all,  their  coverts  are  foresaking; 
The  winds  of  morning  freshen  as  they  blow: 
Athwart  the  plain  the  deer  with  antlers  shaking, 
Athwart  the  sky  the  singing  wildwings  go! 
Awake,  awake!     While  dewy  Earth  is  making 
The  springs  of  life  with  morning  gladness  flow ! 

Day  is  here! 

Day  is  here,  is  here,  is  here! 

Day  is  here,  is  here! 

The  song  ceases  with  the  Fathers  to  the  North  of  the  Altar,  the  Children  to 
the  South,  all  facing  toward  it,  their  parallel  files  forming  a  broad 
avenue  from  the  Center  Gate  to  the  Forefront. 

THEME  VIII. 

The  music  becomes  strong  and  broad,  developing  the  motive  of  the  creation 

of  light  and  life  and  the  mystery  of  revelation. 
From  the  Center  there  enter,  in  single  file:  An  Acolyte  bearing  the  spread 

wings,  carried  as  a  banner;  an  Acolyte  bearing  the  white-plumed  wand; 


378  THE  MONIST. 

an  Acolyte  bearing  a  tray  upon  which  is  fire  and  tobacco;  at  a  distance, 
the  Leader,  as  one  inspired.  The  three  Acolytes  advance  to  the  Fore- 
front; the  Leader  remains  before  the  Altar. 

The  two  Chiefs  with  their  calumets  go  before  the  Acolytes.  They  take  the 
fire  and  the  tobacco  and  offer  a  smoke-offering  to  Heaven.  Then  the 
Acolytes,  in  single  file  as  before,  withdraw  through  the  Center;  the 
Chiefs  retire  to  their  stations. 

The  Leader,  with  uplifted  gaze,  intones  the  Psalm  of  Revelation : 


With  brooding  mystery. 

As  I  lay  sleeping, 

As  I  lay  dreaming, 

Out  of  the  distance  came  one  advancing, 

Out  of  the  distance  came  one  descending, 

As  cometh  a  star  from  the  deep  of  Heaven, 

As  cometh  a  star  in  a  pool  of  light, 

Welling  to  fullness, 

Welling  in  stillness, 

Till  resteth  its  ray 

On  the  brim  of  the  World. 

As  I  lay  sleeping, 

As  I  lay  dreaming, 

Out  of  the  distance  one  came  flying, 

Out  of  the  distance,  with  whirring  of  wings .... 

As  I  lay  sleeping, 

As  I  lay  dreaming, 

Over  me  drooped  her  glittering  wings, 

Over  me  drooped,  while  she  chanted  the  mystic 

Spell  of  the  riddle  that  ruleth  the  World. 

As  I  lay  sleeping, 

As  I  lay  dreaming, 

She  sang  me  the  Song  of  the  Eldest  of  Mornings, 

She  sang  me  the  deeds  of  the  Father  creative, 

She  sang  me  the  cure  of  the  leaderless  life. . . . 

As  I  lay  sleeping, 

As  I  lay  dreaming, 

She  read  me  the  riddle  that  ruleth  the  World. 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  379 

II. 

With  austere  solemnity: 

How  they  that  were  above  were  in  Darkness 

And  they  that  were  below  were  in  Darkness: 

When  over  all  things  brooded  the  Night,  heavily .... 

Silent  were  all  things, 

All  lay  hushed. 

Then  the  Father  of  Heaven  breathed  the  Breath  of  Life ; 

Then  the  Father  of  Heaven  moved  upon  the  face  of  Darkness, 

Upon  the  Body  of  Night, 

Upon  the  body  of  the  Mother  of  Day, 

Moved  the  Father  of  Heaven, 

Breathing  the  Breath  of  Life. 

A  Child  to  the  Night  is  born ! 
.Unto  the  Father  of  Heaven  and  unto  the  Night 
Is  born  the  Dawn .... 
Whose  breath  is  the  Breath  of  Life, 
Whose  gift  is  the  Gift  of  Life 
Unto  all  things. 

A  Child  to  the  Night  is  born ! 

Yea,  the  Dawn, 

Whose  father  is  the  Father  of  Heaven 

And  whose  mother  is  the  Night .... 

And  all  things  above 

And  all  things  below 

Are  quickened  into  being. 

in. 
As  at  first: 

As  I  lay  sleeping, 

As  I  lay  dreaming, 

She  sang  me  the  Song  of  the  Eldest  of  Mornings, 

She  sang  me  the  deeds  of  the  Father  of  All. 

IV. 

Solemnly,  but  with  enthusiasm : 

Then  the  Father  of  Heaven  created  the  Chieftain  Sun : 
Who  is  sire  of  the  shining  Day; 


380  THE  MONIST. 

Who  is  leader  of  the  Wardens  of  Light ; 

Who  holdeth  the  measures  of  the  years. 

His  spouse  is  our  Mother  Earth, 

His  warmth  is  the  warmth  of  all  that  live, 

Gladness  is  his  offspring: 

Whom  the  Father  created  Chieftain  of  the  Skies. 

Yea,  the  Father  of  Heaven  united  Earth  and  Sun 

In  Holy  Marriage, 

Whereof  are  born  her  breathing  Children — 

Bird  and  beast  and  mortal  men — 

And  all  her  living  fruits : 

The  Father  of  Heaven  united  Earth  and  Sun, 

Whose  Child  is  mortal  Life. 

v. 
As  at  first: 

As  I  lay  sleeping, 

As  I  lay  dreaming, 

Lo,  in  a  Vision  one  came  revealing 

The  Mystery  of  Life. 

VI.  i 

With  exaltation : 

Give  heed !     Give  heed ! 

Give  heed,  O  ye  People! 

Unto  the  Abode  of  Life  give  ye  heed, 

And  unto  the  Powers  thereof 

Let  your  hearts  be  turned  in  reverence .... 

The  Leader  remains  beside  the  Altar. 

THEME  IX. 

The  Chorus  moves  in  stately  alternation  of  the  Semi-Choruses,  chanting  their 
antiphon  to  Earth  and  Sun. 

Semi-Chorus  of  Fathers: 

Now  behold!   Hither  cometh  the  ray  of  our  Father  Sun, 
Over  all  the  land,  us  to  touch  and  give  us  strength ! 

Semi-Chorus  of  Children: 

We  think  on  Mother  Earth  who  lieth  here: 
We  know  she  giveth  of  her  fruitfulness. 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  381 

Semi-Chorus  of  Fathers : 

Now  behold!     Where  mounteth  up  our  Father  Sun! 
Into  the  Lodge  of  Heaven  he  mounteth  up. 

Semi-Chorus  of  Children: 

Behold  on  Mother  Earth  the  growing  fields: 
Behold  the  promise  of  her  f ruitfulness ! 

Semi-Chorus  of  Fathers : 

Now  behold !    Through  all  the  World  our  Father  Sun 
Sendeth  his  rays,  the  Messengers  of  Light! 

Semi-Chorus  of  Children: 

We  think  on  Mother  Earth  who  lieth  here: 
We  see  the  promise  of  her  fruitfulness. 

Semi-Chorus  of  Fathers : 

Now  behold !    How  all  the  life  of  hill  and  plain 
Is  quickened  by  the  rays  of  our  Father  Sun! 

Semi-Chorus  of  Children: 

Give  thanks  to  Mother  Earth  for  trees  and  streams ; 
Give  thanks  to  Mother  Earth  for  growing  fields; 
Give  thanks  to  Mother  Earth  for  ripened  corn; 
Give  thanks  to  Mother  Earth  for  food  and  life! 

Semi-Chorus  of  Fathers: 

Now  behold!     Where  goeth  down  our  Father  Sun, 
Who  of  his  strength  this  day  of  life  hath  given! 

Semi-Chorus  of  Children: 

We  think  on  Mother  Earth  who  lieth  here: 
Truly,  her  power  she  hath  given  us! 

Semi-Chorus  of  Fathers : 

Now  behold !    Where  sinketh  low  our  Father  Sun 

Upon  the  margent  of  the  glowing  West ! . . . . 

So  is  the  life  of  man  led  forth 

Out  of  the  Night,  through  Morn  and  Noon  and  Eve, 

To  sink  into  the  silent  Night  again ! 

Semi-Chorus  of  Children: 

We  think  on  Mother  Earth  who  lieth  here.  . 


382  THE  MONIST. 

THEME  X. 

The  mysterious  music  of  the  inaugural  is  resumed,  but  with  a  deeper,  more 
austere  meaning.  The  Chorus  forms  for  the  outgoing.  Then  the 
Leader,  with  arms  outspread: 

There  is  none  persuadeth  Death! 

The  old  men  have  not  told  how  any  hath  found  a  way. 

The  career  of  a  Leader  is  difficult! 

Marching  counter,  as  in  their  entrance,  the  Fathers  and  the  Children  circle 
the  sward  and  pass  out  at  their  respective  gates,  chanting : 

Holy  Visions,  ye  of  yore 
To  our  Fathers  came  revealing; 
Hither  come,  O  come  once  more, 
To  our  troubled  lives  with  healing! 

Holy  Visions,  ye  who  bring 
From  the  starlit  Sky  her  glories, 
Hither  come  on  shining  wing, 
Pause  ye  where  the  open  door  is : 

Pause  ye  at  the  open  gate, 
Enter  at  the  silent  portal, 
Bless  the  hearts  of  them  that  wait 
With  the  grace  of  light  immortal: 

With  the  grace  of  holy  sight 
To  the  dream-life  of  the  dreamer 
Ye  shall  come,  and  guide  aright: 
He  shall  know  his  life's  redeemer. 

Holy  visions !     As  of  yore 
To  our  Sires  ye  came  revealing, 
Come,  O  come  to  us  once  more, 
With  the  mystery  of  healing! 

[As  the  last  of  the  Chorus  is  disappearing,  the  Leader  retires,  solitary.] 


PART  III.   THE  MYSTERY. 

THEME  XL 

From  the  North  and  South  Gates  the  Fathers  and  the  Children,  except  their 
Chiefs,  who  remain  behind,  enter  in  an  animated  and  swift-scattering 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  383 

movement,  giving  the  effect  of  individual  wheelings  and  circlings  and 
poisings  over  the  whole  plaza.  The  music  is  lively  and  full  of  bird 
themes. 

The  Chorus : 

Hark,  hark!    The  birds! 

The  birds  are  a-wing! 

Earth  and  Sky  are  alive 

Where  they  flit,  where  they  swing ! 

Where  they  dip,  where  they  dive, 

And  down  the  winds  drive, 

Till  with  whir  and  with  whing 

Of  thunderous  wing 

The  volleying  air 

Is  a-blare,  is  a-blare! 

Rising,  circling,  dipping,  fleeting, 

Now  they  rest,  and  now  they  haste ! 
Coming,  going,  parting,  meeting, 
Bird  to  bird  his  cry  repeating : 

"Summer  nest  is  Wintry  waste! 
"Winter  stealeth  Summer  pleasure, 

"Garb  of  green  he  turneth  gray: 
"Where  the  winds  bear  Summer's  treasure, 

"Thither,  thither,  haste  away !" 

Flutt'ring,  flocking,  flitting,  flying, 
Now  they  rest,  and  now  they  haste, 

Bird  to  answering  bird  a-crying: 
"Summer  nest  is  Wintry  waste!" 

Individual  singers,  one  by  one,  sing  the  songs  of  the  birds,  with  mimetic 
action. 

The  Song  of  the  Nestling : 

O'er  the  prairie,  o'er  the  prairie, 

Round  about  me  as  I  walk, 
How  the  shadows  flit  in  circles — 
Mischief  shadows,  making  mock! 

'Tis  the  birds  above  wide  circling, 
'Tis  their  shadows  on  the  ground : 

As  when  parent  birds  protecting 
Feeble  nestlings  circle  round. 


384  THE  MONIST. 

Birds  of  Heaven,  Birds  of  Heaven, 
We,  your  nestlings,  joyous  cry 

When  His  sign  of  care  ye  give  us, 
Wheeling  in  the  azure  sky ! 

The  Song  of  the  Wren : 

Whe  kee  re  re  wee  chee! 
Whe  kee  re  re  wee  chee! 

Joy,  joy,  joy! 
Singeth  the  tiny  Wren: 
And  shall  not  men 
Know  joy? 

The  Song  of  the  Duck : 

Lo,  the  Finder-Out  of  Ways— 
The  Bird  of  the  Emerald  Crest— 
The  Bird  who  never  strays, 

But  doth  fare 
In  arrowy  flight  and  ware 
Over  water  and  earth  and  air, 

North  and  South, 

East  and  West 

Oh,  the  speeding  Scout  of  the  Skies 
Knoweth  their  quartering  ties : 
As  the  Leader  of  Men  must  know 
Where  the  paths  of  Heaven  go! 

The  Song  of  the  Owl: 

He!     HiriWahoru! 

He!     Hiri  Wahoru! 

Wide-eyed  Bird  of  the  Night, 
Who  seest  invisible  things 
And  spreadest  thy  shadowy  wings 
In  dim  and  inaudible  flight.  . .  . 

He!    HiriWahoru! 

He!     Hiri  Wahoru! 

Let  ours  be  the  gift  of  thy  sight! 

Full  Chorus: 

Oh,  the  Bird,  the  Birds! 
The  Birds  are  a-wing! 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  385 

Like  sky-blown  herds 
At  the  wintry  sting 
Which  the  North 

Striketh  forth 

Where  they  come, 

Where  they  go, 

All  the  air 

Is  a-blare, 

All  the  air  is  a-thrum, 

As  with  beating  of  drum 

And  sounding  of  string 

Where  drawn  is  the  bow 

And  the  swift  arrows  sing ! .  . .  . 

Oh,  the  Birds  are  a-wing! 

Summer  flown, 
Nestlings  grown, 
Southward  blown 
Wide  a-wing! 

The  Chorus  ends  its  evolutions  with  the  two  divisions  forming,  as  it  were, 
encircling  wings,  across  the  Forefront,  and  facing  Northwest  and  South- 
west, so  as  to  view  the  gates. 

THEME  XII. 

The  temper  of  the  music  becomes  more  grave,  with  the  flutes  of  the  Eagle 
dominant. 

Semi-Chorus  of  Fathers : 

Behold,  an  Eagle  now  is  circling,  widely  circling  above  us ! 

Semi-Chorus  of  Children : 

As  the  mother-bird  circleth  her  nestlings,  careful  for  her 

chicks, 
She  circleth  us,  hovering. . . . 

Full  Chorus: 

She  is  the  Eagle  of  God! 

Of  Him  who  is  Father  of  Heaven, 

Who  ruleth  the  zoned  Earth 

And  sendeth  His  will  by  the  Eagle 

Over  the  windy  Pathways 

That  lead  from  Man  up  to  God ! . . . . 


386  THE  MONIST. 

The  motive  of  the  music  is  the  poignancy  of  human  aspiration. 

From  the  North  Gate,  the  Gate  of  the  Fathers,  enter-.  An  Acolyte  with  the 
Spread  Wings,  borne  as  a  banner;  an  Acolyte  with  the  Corn,  one  with 
the  Bowl,  one  with  Tray  and  Cups;  the  Leader,  with  wand;  an  Acolyte 
with  the  white-plumed  wand.  They  march  in  single  file,  their  path  a 
semi-circle  from  the  North  to  the  South  Gate,  around  the  Altar.  At 
the  Altar  they  stop. 

The  Leader: 

I  know  not  if  the  voice  of  man  can  reach  unto  the  Skies ; 
I  know  not  if  the  Silent  One  can  hear  me  as  I  pray ; 
I  know  not  if  my  words  be  foolish  words  or  wise ; 
I  know  not  if  I  walk  in  straight  or  crooked  way. 

I  only  know  His  power,  Who  hath  made  our  mortal  lot 
An  hurt  and  stumbling  pace  led  outward  through  the  dark ; 
I  only  know  his  trust,  Who  lest  He  be  forgot, 
Hath  weathered  deep  the  soul  of  man  with  an  immortal  mark. 

As  they  move  on  toward  the  South  Gate,  the  Gate  of  the  Children,  the  Aco- 
lytes sing,  in  choral: 

Father,  unto  thee  we  cry ! 
Father  of  all  we  hear  and  see, 
Father  of  all  we  feel  and  hope, 
Author  of  life's  mystery: 
Father,  unto  thee  we  cry ! 

They  pass  out. 


THEME  XIII. 

The  Fathers,  pianissimo  bass,  sing : 

With  the  dawn  will  I  seek  my  child, 
With  the  tenderly  growing  dawn ; 
Where  the  breath  of  the  morn  floweth  on 
I  will  go  seeking  my  child, 
My  little  one,  my  son .... 

With  swelling  music,  the  Children: 

Father,  come  unto  me  here, 
Here  where  I  wait  for  thee, — 
With  bread  and  with  morning  cheer, 
Father,  come  unto  me! 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  387 

The  Fathers: 

I  come,  my  child,  I  come, 
Seeking  for  thee .... 
Abide  me,  and  nothing  fear: 
On  the  wings  of  the  dawn  I  come 
Seeking  for  thee .... 

The  Children: 

See! 

The  Eagle  is  flying  o'er  us! 

In  the  sky  above,  from  the  Father's  home ! 

The  Eagle  descendeth  unto  us 

With  the  Father's  cheer ! 

In  the  music  is  the  note  of  the  dawning  Light.    Then  the  Chorus : 
Behold ! 

The  Star  of  the  East! 
The  Star  of  the  bursting  Morn! 

From  the  Gate  of  the  Children  a  runner,  personator  of  the  Morning  Star,  clad 
all  in  red,  the  color  of  life,  and  in  his  hair  a  red  plume,  symbolic  of  the 
breath  of  life.  To  his  arms  are  attached  spread  wings.  Sweeping  past, 
he  cries: 

A  Child  is  born! 

Unto  Man  a  Child  is  born! 

Unto  Man  is  born  a  Son ! 

He  passes  forth  by  the  North  Gate,  the  Gate  of  the  Fathers. 
The  Chorus: 

A  Child  is  born !    A  Child  is  born  ! 

An  holy  Child  is  born! 

Stars  of  the  Morning  rejoice! 

Life  is  renewed  in  the  World ! 

The  music  swells  with  prophetic  exaltation. 

Enter  from  the  Holy  Gate:  The  Acolyte  with  the  Spread  Wings;  the  Acolyte 
with  the  Corn,  he  with  the  Bowl,  he  with  the  Tray  on  which  are  the 
four  cups;  the  Acolyte  with  the  white-plumed  Wand;  the  Leader;  the 
Chief  of  the  Fathers,  carrying  the  Child;  the  Chief  of  the  Children. 

When  all  are  entered  the  Leader  takes  the  Child  and  holds  him  aloft,  crying : 
Behold  the  Child! 


388  THE  MONIST. 

The  Chorus: 

Behold  the  Child! 

Behold  the   Promised  One! 

The  Leader  returns  the  Child  to  the  Chief  of  the  Fathers,  on  either  side  of 
whom  the  Acolytes  range  themselves,  and  leads  the  way  to  the  Altar, 
while  the  Acolytes  sing : 

Here  we  go  singing,  singing, .... 

Looking  on  the  Child — 

The  little  Child  who  leadeth  us, 

Borne  in  his  father's  arms: 

Here  we  go  singing,  singing.  . .  . 

Looking  on  the  Child. 

THEME  XIV. 

At  the  Altar  they  form:  the  Leader  a  few  paces  in  advance,  at  his  left  the 
Chief  of  the  Fathers  zvith  the  Child  and  the  Chief  of  the  Children;  the 
Acolytes  ranged  before  the  Altar,  the  white-plumed  Wand  to  the  North, 
the  Spread  Wings  to  the  South. 

The  Leader  spreads  his  hands,  like  spread  wings,  above  the  Child.  He  sig- 
nals to  the  Acolyte  with  the  tray  and  cups,  who  advances.  The  Leader 
dips  his  finger  into  one  of  the  cups  and  touches  the  Child,  drawing  a 
semi-circle  about  his  brow. 

The  Leader: 

With  the  Blue  of  the  Skies  I  anoint  thee .... 

The  Chorus: 

That  thou  may'st  long  abide  beneath  the  Lodge  of  Heaven. 

The  Leader  dips  his  finger  into  a  second  cup  and  draws  it  across  the  Child's 
chin : 

With  the  Green  of  the  Earth  I  anoint  thee .... 

The  Chorus : 

That  thy  feet  may  be  led  amid  fruitful  fields. 

Dipping  into  a  third  cup  and  touching  the  Child's  cheeks: 

With  the  Crimson  of  Life  I  anoint  thee.  . .  . 

The  Chorus: 

That  strength  and  vigor  shall  be  thine  in  youth  and  age. 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  389 

Dipping  into  the  fourth  cup  the  Leader  touches  the  Child's  brow : 
With  Oil  and  with  Fat  I  anoint  thee .... 

The  Chorus: 

That  peace  and  plenty  may  follow  thee  all  thy  days. 

The  Acolyte  retires;  the  Leader  once  more  spreads  his  hands  above  the  Child; 
a  second  Acolyte  advances,  bearing  the  Corn.  The  Leader  taking  it, 
strokes  the  Child's  body : 

I  stroke  thee  with  the  ripened  Corn .... 

The  Chorus : 

So  may  thy  body's  needs  be  satisfied! 

The  Acolyte  with  the  Bowl  advances.     The  Leader  sprinkles  the  Child: 
I  refresh  thee  with  the  clear  and  running  stream .... 

The  Chorus : 

So  may  thy  generations  run  onward  without  ceasing. 

The  Acolytes  retire.  The  Leader  takes  from  his  hair  the  white  eagle-down 
and  fastens  it  in  the  Child's  hair: 

With  this  sacred  token  I  thee  adorn — 
Symbol  of  the  fleecy  clouds  above, 
Symbol  of  the  winds  of  Heaven, 
Symbol  of  the  living  breath 
Into  the  body  of  man 
Breathed  by  the  Father 

After  a  pause,  his  hands  resting  on  the  Child's  head: 

Enter  ye  into  the  House  of  Life,  consecrate. 

He  returns  the  Child  to  the  Chief  of  the  Fathers.     Then  triumphantly: 
I  know  now  that  the  voice  of  man  can  reach  the  skies ; 
I  know  now  that  the  Mighty  One  can  hear  me  as  I  pray ; 
I  know  our  Father  answereth  his  children's  troubled  cries, 
And  pace  by  pace  assigneth  us  the  token  of  the  way. 

Give  heed  !     Give  heed ! 

Give  heed,  O  ye  People! 

Unto  the  Abode  of  Life  give  ye  heed, 

And  unto  the  Powers  thereof 

Let  your  hearts  be  turned  in  reverence .... 


390  THE  MONIST. 


THEME  XV. 

The  music  becomes  reminiscent  of  the  Chant  of  the  Way  of  Life.  The  Chorus 
moves  forward,  forming  a  circle,  the  Children  within,  the  Fathers 
without,  as  in  the  figure  of  the  lodge.  The  Leader  advances  beyond 
the  Altar  and  paces  a  small  circle,  or  symbolic  lodge.  The  two  Chiefs 
enter  this  circle  while  the  Acolytes,  with  emblems  raised  as  in  blessing, 
form  a  semi-circle  behind. 

The  Chief  of  the  Children  takes  the  Child  from  the  Chief  of  the  Fathers. 
Then  the  Chief  of  the  Fathers  moves  forward  and  sings: 

Within  the  House  of  Life  man  entereth 
A  little  Child  with  slow  and  faltering  feet: 

The  breathing  Heaven  is  in  his  fluttering  breath, 
The  pulse  of  Earth  in  his  swift  blood  doth  beat. 

Within  the  House  of  Life  man  tarrieth, 
As  one  who  for  a  season  taketh  rest: 

The  Blue  above,  below  the  grassy  Earth, — 
An  oriole  within  a  wind-swept  nest. 

Within  the  House  of  Life  man  offereth 

The  simple  tokens  of  his  daily  need, 
His  prayer  for  food  and  drink,  in  humble  faith 

That  some  dim  distant  Power  shall  give  them  heed. 

Then  from  the  House  of  Life  he  hasteneth. . . . 

Aye,  as  an  Eagle  in  his  feathered  mail 
Battleth  adown  the  blast  with  windy  Death, 

Speedeth  the  Warrior-Soul  with  battle-hail ! 

The  Chorus  is  in  motion,  moving  in  a  strange  dance  simulating  the  -flight  of 
eagles.  They  form  in  files  and  circle  about  the  central  group.  They  sing : 

Come,  ye  Fathers! 

Come,  ye  Children! 

Come,  ye  People, — 

Mortal  men ! 

Into  the  House  of  Life,  come  enter! 

Into  the  House — the  Way  is  open : 

Enter  in,  O  mortal  men ! .  . .  . 

Like  flocking  birds, 

Like  shouting  eagles, 

Full  of  joy  and  lust  of  life, 


THE  MYSTERY  OF  LIFE.  39! 

Swiftly,  swiftly,  swiftly  come  ye, — 
Enter  in,  O  mortal  men ! .  . .  . 
As  your  Fathers  came  before  you, 
As  a  little  child  doth  come, 
Where  the  Way  is  open,  open, 
Enter  in,  O  mortal  men ! .  . .  . 

As  they  cease,  the  tzvo  groups,  the  Fathers  and  the  Children,  are  formed,  on 
the  North  and  the  South,  like  the  spread  wings  of  an  Eagle.  The  two 
Chiefs,  in  the  center,  are  the  bird's  body;  the  Acolytes,  with  the  em- 
blems, have  retreated,  forming,  as  it  were,  the  tail  plumes;  the  Leader, 
with  the  Child,  has  advanced  to  the  head. 

There  falls  an  utter  stillness.  The  Leader  uplifts  the  Child,  looking  upward. 
In  a  penetrating  voice  he  cries : 

Breathe  on  him! 

Breathe  on  him! 

Life  thou  alone  canst  give  him : 

Long  life,  we  pray,  O  Father,  give  unto  him ! 

Mid  swelling  music,  like  the  march  of  the  tribes  and  nations  of  men,  exeunt 
omnes. 

THE    END. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

BERGSON  AND  RELIGION. 

Henri  Bergson  is  probably  the  most  potential  name  in  modern 
philosophy.  Prof.  William  James,  who  was  by  common  consent  our 
most  distinguished  thinker,  though  he  was  much  older,  called  Pro- 
fessor Bergson  "master  and  teacher."  This,  certainly,  is  high  praise. 

Aside  from  his  speculative  capacity,  Professor  Bergson  is  a  most 
interesting  figure.  He  is  an  earnest  student  of  physiology,  biology 
and  psychology,  and  he  brings  to  his  philosophical  theories  a  great 
wealth  of  scientific  illustration  and  proof.  And  unlike  so  many  of 
our  great  metaphysicians,  he  has  literary  power,  the  gift  of  musical 
speech.  Whether  the  Evolution  creatrice  is  great  art  like  the  Corin- 
thians of  Paul,  the  Divine  Comedy,  "Lycidas,"  or  "Les  Miserables," 
it  may  be  too  soon  to  decide.  But  it  is  certainly  a  work  of  art,  and 
of  no  mean  order.  Professor  Bergson  is  a  personality,  and  his 
thought  is  always  suggestive  and  commands  attention. 

It  is  interesting  to  watch  the  flight  of  his  speculative  'arrows, 
even  though  we  fail  to  see  that  they  strike  any  target.  Nevertheless, 
in  my  judgment  he  has  made  one  vital  suggestion,  which  I  shall 
indicate  in  the  course  of  this  study.  But  first  I  shall  attempt  to 
trace  his  theory  of  the  universe  and  his  theory  of  truth  and  show 
their  philosophical  and  religious  meaning  and  influence. 

As  every  one  comes  to  a  study  with  certain  prepossessions,  I 
may  say  that  I  am  not  a  materialist,  idealist  or  pragmatist,  but  con- 
ceive there  are  in  man  elements  not  mechanical  and  that  he  has, 
within  narrow  limits,  the  power  of  choice. 

Professor  Bergson  in  his  theory  makes  an  immeasurable  pri- 
meval "super-consciousness"  the  source  of  all  things,  of  life  and 
matter.  This  unique  creative  absolute  has  will,  freedom,  and  an 
impulse  to  create,  but  strange  to  say,  though  it  has  this  consciousness 
and  spontaneity,  it  has  not  intelligence.  It  moves  on  and  on,  ever 
unfolding,  ever  augmenting,  with  no  design  or  purpose,  seeking 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  393 

no  predetermined  goal,  for  M.  Bergson  frowns  upon  all  forms  of 
teleology. 

This  theory  of  a  great  life-river,  if  I  may  so  describe  it,  ever 
seeking  to  find  new  channels  of  creative  opportunity,  I  found  to 
my  surprise  was  similar  to  that  of  my  friend,  Prof.  F.  C.  Doan, 
published  in  the  Journal  of  Philosophy  about  two  years  before  the 
"Creative  Evolution"  appeared.  I  learned,  since  commencing  this 
paper,  that  Professor  James  had  made  the  same  discovery.  And  I 
may  say  that,  leaving  off  certain  naive  features  in  the  book  of  Gen- 
esis, M.  Bergson's  theory  of  the  origin  of  the  world  reminds  me  of 
that  great  sentence :  "In  the  beginning,  God." 

Whence  comes  this  vast  energy  with  its  impulse  to  create,  M. 
Bergson  does  not  tell.  He  asserts  that  from  it  spring  both  life  and 
matter  and  that  every  living  thing,  from  the  lichen  on  the  rock  to 
the  golden  dandelion  nodding  in  the  south  wind,  from  the  ameba 
to  the  man,  possesses  consciousness  and  freedom,  and  these  qualities 
enmeshed  and  entangled  in  matter,  reduced  or  attenuated  to  the 
finest  threads,  are  never  lost.  At  times  Professor  Bergson  calls 
matter  "the  enemy"  of  all  good.  It  is  ever  to  be  resisted,  it  must  be 
transmuted  into  living  organisms,  it  must  be  saturated  with  "con- 
tingency." 

Again  he  calls  the  resistance  of  matter  a  "stimulus."  It  is  by 
the  reduction  of  the  flesh,  by  the  chastening  of  the  senses,  that  men 
become  healthy,  strong  and  beautiful. 

It  will  be  seen  that  in  this  dogma  of  the  life-urge,  M.  Bergson 
strenuously  opposes  the  new  naturalism  so  popular  at  the  close  of 
the  last  century.  He  affirms  that  life  always  has  in  it  the  seeds  of 
freedom  or  contingency,  that  contingency  grows  greater  as  organ- 
isms develop.  He  cannot  believe  that  the  high  reason  that  has  traced 
the  laws  of  the  earth  and  measured  the  stars,  that  the  hope,  affection, 
imagination  which  blossomed  into  the  melodious  words  of  the  Ser- 
mon on  the  Mount  are  the  product  of  mechanical  and  unintelligent 
forces — that  blind  physical  atoms  could  in  time  stumble  into  an 
orderly  living  universe ! 

Has  Professor  Bergson  spoken  a  deep,  living  word?  Has  he 
made  a  new  synthesis?  There  are  many  who  believe  that  he  has. 
He  opposes  the  older  idealism  of  Kant,  Hegel  and  Fichte,  and  the 
"absolute"  of  such  teachers  as  Royce  and  Bradley  in  his  theory  of 
time.  For  unlike  them,  he  makes  time  a  reality,  and  in  time  creation 
begins.  His  theory  of  this  original  creative  energy  makes  the  uni- 
verse of  life  and  matter  a  great  Mississippi  life-river,  ever  flowing 


394  THE  MONIST. 

on.  Its  course  may  be  traced  in  the  past  and  in  the  present,  but  its 
course  in  the  future,  he  says,  no  one,  however  wise,  can  trace. 

That  the  future  is  impenetrably  veiled  (an  idea  I  have  long 
contended  for),  Professor  Bergson  urges  from  the  fact  that  the  uni- 
verse is  not  made  but  making.  There  is  ever  the  condition  of  un- 
certainty, of  spontaneity,  of  contingency,  and  thence  may  come  the 
unexpected.  We  see  now  the  leaf,  the  stalk,  the  bud,  but  of  the 
glory  and  beauty  of  the  flower  and  fruit,  none  can  know. 

M.  Bergson's  opposition  to  materialism  is  seen  in  his  radical 
idea  of  freedom.  He  maintains  that  in  all  living  organisms  there  is 
something  that  cannot  be  accounted  for  by  the  laws  of  matter.  There 
is  in  them  a  power  which  draws  from  itself  more  than  it  receives, 
"gives  more  than  has  been  given  to  it."  There  is  something  free 
in  the  violet,  the  bird,  the  man,  not  produced  by  reflex  action.  There 
is  a  tiny  will,  a  drop  of  beauty,  of  will,  of  love,  of  intelligence,  which 
is  pure  creation.  There  is  ever  the  quality  of  the  contingent,  the  new, 
the  unforeseen,  for  this  is  a  "spiritual  universe." 

Of  course  the  idealist  will  say  that  Professor  Bergson's  theory 
destroys  the  timelessness  and  omniscience  of  the  Absolute,  and  the 
naturalist  will  ask  for  proof.  He  will  inquire,  why  it  was  necessary 
to  invent  a  "superconsciousness"  to  start  the  universe.  He  will 
say  it  is  just  as  easy  to  think  of  life  evolving  from  matter,  as  matter 
from  life;  and  the  idealist  will  be  alarmed  at  the  thought  of  ad- 
mitting into  the  universe  the  element  of  imperfection  and  the  un- 
foreseen. 

But  we  must  now  come  to  the  more  original,  and  more  radical 
part  of  his  theory,  his  theory  of  truth.  The  extreme  radicalism  of 
his  idea  may  be  seen  from  the  fact  that  M.  Bergson  makes  "not 
reason  but  instinct  bring  us  into  the  closest  touch,  the  directest  rela- 
tion with  what  is  most  real  in  the  universe,"  to  use  the  words  of 
Mr.  Balfour.  In  this,  I  may  say  that  Professor  Bergson  follows  the 
present  tendency  to  distrust  the  power  of  the  intellect  to  reach  a 
reasonable  explanation  of  the  universe — to  prove  the  existence  of 
God,  of  freedom,  of  immortality.  All  questions  of  ultimates  are 
beyond  intellectual  search.  The  intellect  is  limited  to  the  sphere  of 
experience. 

Professor  Bergson  agrees  with  this  distrust  of  the  intellect,  but 
affirms  that  what  is  impossible  to  the  intellect  is  possible  to  instinct. 
The  province  of  reason  is  not  life,  freedom,  spirituality,  but  matter, 
mechanics  and  space,  "the  waste  products  of  the"  life-urge.  James 
agrees  with  his  teacher  here,  for  he  says  that  "the  reason  can  know 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  395 

only  surfaces."  But,  one  may  ask,  are  not  these  statements  purely 
dogmatic,  speculative? 

Professor  Bergson,  while  he  admits  the  immeasurably  wider 
horizons  of  the  human  intellect,  asserts  that  instinct,  in  ants  and  bees 
in  which  it  comes  to  its  perfect  flower,  is  in  touch  with  a  higher 
order  of  truth.  Maeterlinck  makes  a  similar  assertion  in  his  work 
on  the  bees. 

But  surely  there  lie  innumerable  difficulties  in  the  path  of  this 
fantastic  theory.  If  the  instinct  of  the  Hymenopterae  is  the  infallible 
organ  for  the  discovery  of  knowledge,  why  is  it  that  they  do  not  ad- 
vance, but  keep  in  the  same  monotonous  round?  With  this  great 
power,  why  is  their  achievement  so  limited,  their  vision  so  narrow? 
Why  should  they  have  so  much  of  this  divine  power,  and  man,  who 
is  so  incomparably  greater,  have  so  little?  With  this  great  endow- 
ment, wherein  have  they  advanced  beyond  him? 

Professor  Bergson  tells  of  a  certain  kind  of  wasp,  the  fossorial, 
which,  instead  of  killing  its  victim,  stings  it  into  unconsciousness 
by  a  most  delicate  surgical  act.  This  mechanical  skill,  he  says,  does 
not  come  as  the  result  of  numberless  experiments,  and  it  would 
be  forever  impossible^  to  intelligence,  but  it  comes  through  that  in- 
stinct which  reveals  to  the  wasp  the  secret  of  life  itself. 

Does  it  not  seem  fantastic,  to  say  the  least,  that  the  instinct  of 
the  fossorial  wasp  can  reach  a  higher  truth  than  the  most  sustained 
efforts  of  a  great  intellect?  Can  the  work  or  conquests  of  the  ants 
and  bees  compare  with  the  magnificent  achievements  of  the  human 
intellect  in  mathematical,  physical  and  moral  science?  Do  we  come 
into  nearer  touch  with  reality  in  the  cell  of  an  ant  than  in  a  painting 
by  Titian  ? 

It  is  true  that  the  instincts  are  nearest  the  primeval  forces,  and 
may  guide  us  best  in  the  things  of  the  flesh.  Instinct  may,  by  a  sort 
of  divine  unreason,  go  straight  to  the  heart  of  the  lower  truth,  but  to 
solve  the  supreme  problems,  the  meaning  of  life,  the  existence  of 
God,  of  freedom  and  of  immortality  must  be  an  achievement  of  the 
highest  intellect. 

But  it  would  not  be  fair  to  M.  Bergson,  not  to  explain  that  these 
mystical  assertions,  these  speculative  dreams,  are  enmeshed  in  a 
profusion  of  scientific  illustration.  He  shows  a  minute  and  wide 
knowledge  of  physiology,  biology  and  natural  history,  and  in  his 
boldest  speculative  flights  always  makes  his  final  appeal  to  concrete 
facts. 

But  now  I  come  to  the  question  that  will  arise  in  many  minds : 


396  THE  MONIST. 

Is  the  philosophy  of  Professor  Bergson  religious  in  the  highest 
sense  ?  Does  it  make  its  appeal  to  our  spiritual  faith  and  aspirations  ? 

Though  this  philosophy  is  radically  opposed  to  the  mechanical 
and  atheistical  tendencies  of  naturalism,  many  will  say  it  cannot  be 
called  religious,  as  M.  Bergson  certainly  means  it  to  be.  It  is  true, 
the  Christian  may  see  theism  in  the  primeval  life-urge,  which  is  the 
source  of  matter  and  all  living  things,  and  in  the  exaltation  of  the 
instinct  a  recognition  of  the  validity  of  the  religious  intuitions ;  but 
it  will  be  difficult  for  the  intelligent  man  to  see  a  real  theism  in  this 
primeval  creative  consciousness,  though  it  has  the  will  to  create  and 
freedom,  but  has  no  plan  or  purpose,  nor  directs  the  universe  to  any 
intelligent  goal. 

And  while  in  his  theory  of  evolution  he  escapes  the  difficulty 
or  dilemma  of  the  old  metaphysical  systems  (that  the  imperfections, 
the  evil,  the  sorrows  of  the  universe,  had  been  known  to  God  before 
He  created  it,  and  were  of  His  own  selection),  it  does  seem  difficult 
to  feel  the  sense  of  worship  in  the  thought  of  a  universe  ever  evolv- 
ing, yet  ever  unintelligible  and  unmoral. 

In  the  pluralism  of  Professor  James,  though  he  calls  himself 
a  pupil  of  Bergson,  there  is  something  for  the  common  mind  to 
catch  hold  of.  When  he  says  that  God  is  the  deepest  power  in  the 
universe  and  is  a  personality,  that  "man  and  God  have  purposes 
for  which  they  care  and  each  can  hear  the  other's  call,"  he  makes 
an  appeal  to  the  humblest  believer.  But  I  fear  that  the  common 
people  will  not  see  the  religious  element  in  the  philosophy  of  Pro- 
fessor Bergson.  The  saints  who  love  and  pray  will  cling  to  the 
thought  of  a  transcendent  God,  leading  the  world  to  a  wise  and 
happy  end,  rather  than  believe  in  this  impersonal  life-force  that 
forever  unfolds,  goes  on  and  on,  but  knows  not  whither  it  is  going. 

On  the  other  hand,  the  scientist  will  have  his  own  thoughts.  He 
sees  that  M.  Bergson,  to  find  an  explanation,  goes  back  to  that  primal 
sea  of  life.  He  will  say  that  he  cannot  discover  wherein  that  is 
different  from  the  theologian's  going  back  to  God. 

Yet,  on  the  whole,  I  should  say  that  the  philosophy  of  Professor 
Bergson  is  theistic  rather  than  atheistic,  and  spiritual  rather  than 
material  and  mechanical. 

I  said  in  the  beginning  of  this  study  that  Professor  Bergson 
had  made,  in  my  judgment,  a  vital  suggestion,  and  that  is  his  recog- 
nition of  the  high  function  of  philosophy.  Although  in  his  theory 
he  remands  the  intellect  to  a  much  lower  place  than  instinct,  he  for- 
gets it  in  practice  when  he  affirms  that  the  vital,  the  supreme  ques- 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  397 

tions,  "What  are  we ;  What  are  we  doing  here ;  and  whence  do  we 
come  and  whither  do  we  go?"  are  the  very  cause  of  philosophy's 
existence',  and  that  the  future  (italics  mine)  will  give  back  to  phi- 
losophy its  rightful  place — the  first. 

Professor  Bergson  does  not  think  that  we  can  arrive  at  objec- 
tive certitude  or  that  we  can  force  assent,  but  he  suggests  that  the 
collection  of  many  facts  and  their  interpretation  may  give  us  a  direc- 
tion, "a  direction  only."  These  "lines  of  facts"  will  give  nothing  but 
a  probability;  "but  all  together,  by  converging  on  the  same  point, 
may  give  us  an  accumulation  of  probabilities  which  will  gradually 
approximate  scientific  certainty." 

It  is  a  pleasure  to  see  the  view  I  have  been  contending  for — 
that  to  this  present  discredit  of  the  intellect,  of  philosophy,  there 
will  come  a  reaction — confirmed  by  the  high  authority  of  Professor 
Bergson.  How  far  the  reality  to  be  known  may  exceed  the  power 
to  know  I  cannot  tell,  but  this  seems  reasonable,  that  the  universe 
has  an  intellectual  answer  to  those  intellectual  questions  with  which 
it  continually  confronts  us.  There  is  in  us  the  indomitable  belief  that 
the  terror  and  mystery  of  the  material  world  may  be  transformed 
by  a  large  knowledge  into  "transparent  formulae."  Should  we  not 
have  the  same  belief  that  the  terror  and  mystery  of  the  moral  and 
religious  worlds  may  be  also,  by  a  larger  intelligence,  transformed 
into  "transparent  formulae"? 

My  study  must  end  here,  and  I  am  aware  how  imperfect  it  has 
been,  but  I  have  tried  to  represent  Professor  Bergson  kindly  and 
impartially.  This  task  has  not  been  easy  for,  as  Mr.  Balfour  says, 
there  are  parts  of  his  theory,  especially  his  theory  of  knowledge, 
difficult  to  comprehend ;  but  I  am  sure  all  will  consent  that  he  has 
broken  open  new  ground,  and  we  can  admit  even  the  exaggeration 
of  Professor  James:  "Open  Bergson  and  new  horizons  loom  on 
every  page  you  read.  It  is  like  the  breath  of  the  morning  and  the 
song  of  birds." 

JAMES  G.  TOWNSEND. 

JAMESTOWN,  N.  Y. 


THE  ANTI-INTELLECTUAL  MOVEMENT  OF  TO-DAY. 

Never  before  in  the  history  of  the  world  has  science  played 
such  a  prominent  part  and  received  more  recognition  as  the  main 
factor  of  civilization.  And  in  truth  there  is  a  general  agreement  as 


398  THE  MONIST. 

to  the  hope  that  we  stand  at  the  threshold  of  the  age  of  science, 
which  means  that  all  problems  of  life  will  be  solved  by  scientific 
inquiry  and  the  old  superstitions  will  be  swept  away.  This  principle 
has  been  applied  to  the  several  domains  of-  life,  to  transportation, 
to  sanitation,  to  the  preparation  of  food  and  medical  problems,  the 
building  of  our  homes  and  public  edifices,  yea  even  to  the  sphere 
of  social  and  religious  life.  It  is  strange,  however,  that  in  these 
very  days  there  have  repeatedly  appeared  philosophical  movements 
which  are  decidedly  anti-intellectual,  and  treat  science  with  a  con- 
tempt in  favor  of  the  instinctive  promptings  of  sentiment,  which  is 
only  paralleled  among  the  most  old-fashioned  dogmatists,  in  the 
tendencies  of  religious  faith  by  such  men  as  Augustine  and  Luther 
who  treat  reason  as  an  enemy  to  faith,  and  endorse  the  old  principle 
Credo  quiet  absurdum. 

We  will  here  make  a  few  comments  in  explanation  of  this  move- 
ment without  taking  sides  either  with  the  admirers  or  the  critics  of 
the  new  fashion.  The  latter,  the  critical  aspect,  is  most  exactly 
represented  by  Mr.  Bertrand  Russell,  pages  321  to  347  of  the  present 
number  of  The  Monist;  the  other  to  some  extent  by  the  Rev.  Dr. 
James  G.  Townsend.  Mr.  Russell  points  out  that  "if  he  (Bergson) 
fails  in  his  condemnation  of  the  intellect,  the  intellect  will  succeed 
in  its  condemnation  of  him." 

It  seems  rather  strange  that  in  the  days  of  the  dawn  of  an  age 
of  science  such  movements  should  be  so  prominent,  but  it  seems  to 
me  that  these  movements  are  the  natural  reaction  against  the  many 
wrong  aspirations  of  science,  for  it  can  not  be  denied  that  the 
prominence  which  science  has  gained  in  our  days  has  also  produced 
a  number  of  narrow-minded  scientists,  who  apply  their  narrow  view 
of  science  to  the  whole  of  life.  To  them  science  is  either  physics 
or  chemistry  or  biochemistry,  or  whatever  their  specialty  may  be, 
and  most  of  them  are  acquainted  with  science  only  in  its  lower 
branches,  mechanics  or  physics  or  some  other  domain  which  is 
void  of  the  higher  development  of  man  where  it  unfolds  itself  in 
social  and  moral  ideas.  Psychology  to  such  minds  is  a  mere  func- 
tion of  the  brain,  and  the  truly  typical  features  of  the  soul  are  an 
accidental  by-play  of  its  coarsest  substratum,  or  to  draw  their  ulti- 
mate conclusion,  mind  is  considered  a  function  of  matter.  Their 
view  of  nature  is  limited,  and  while  they  rob  man  of  his  nobility 
they  degrade  him  into  an  equality  not  only  with  the  brute  but  even 
with  inanimate  existence. 

The  expression  of  this  kind  of  narrow-minded  science  which 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  399 

is  not  true  science  but  the  lowest  step  in  the  development  of  science, 
has  caused  a  distrust  in  the  true  nature  of  science. 

Anti-intellectualism  has  become  fashionable  in  the  philosoph- 
ical world.  Prof.  William  James  made  a  great  propaganda  for  it 
and  succeeded  mainly  by  his  amiable  personality.  He  speaks  in 
the  name  of  a  certain  common  sense  which  stands  up  for  unscien- 
tific views  and  defends  a  pluralism  as  well  as  a  subjectivism  on  the 
ground  that  it  is  based  on  experience.  For  the  same  reason  theory 
is  discredited  for  sheer  love  of  single  and  unrelated  facts.  Facts, 
however,  are  replaced  by  interpretations  of  a  very  primitive  kind, 
among  which  even  belief  in  spirits  plays  an  important  part.  This 
incoherent  system  which  abhors  all  moralism  and  actually  represents 
a  reaction  to  the  world-conception  of  savage  life  goes  under  the 
name  of  pragmatism.  It  has  made  many  conquests  and  gained  many 
brilliant  adherents  even  in  the  stable  circles  of  European  scholar- 
ship. 

Another  center  of  anti-intellectualism  has  been  established  in 
France  of  which  Henri  Bergson  has  become  the  leader  through  his 
unprecedented  brilliancy  of  style  and  oratorical  talent.  He  has 
gained  many  adherents  in  his  own  country,  France,  and  celebrated 
high  triumphs  in  conservative  England.  He  is  expected  in  the 
United  States,  and  we  have  no  doubt  that  he  will  be  welcome  in  the 
circles  of  all  who  are  dissatisfied  with  the  quiet  and  unpretentious 
method  of  patient  inquiry  and  scientific  research.  Men  of  this  type 
possess  great  zeal  and  they  will  naturally  welcome  an  ingenious 
representative  of  their  philosophic  tendencies. 

In  the  meantime  the  spirit  of  criticism  is  stirring  in  England, 
and  we  have  before  us  a  book  which  with  all  soberness  reviews  the 
significance  of  the  new  star  which  has  risen  on  the  philosophical 
horizon.  It  is  written  by  Hugh  S.  R.  Elliot,  LL.  T.,  the  editor  of 
The  Letters  of  John  Stuart  Mill*  Sir  Ray  Lankester,  K.  C.  B., 
F.  R.  S.,  being  invited  to  write  a  few  words  by  way  of  preface  to 
Mr.  Elliot's  book,  says : 

"I  am  glad  to  do  this,  not  merely  because  I  think  that  the  books 
in  which  M.  Bergson  formulates  those  illusions  are  worthless  and 
unprofitable  matter,  causing  waste  of  time  and  confusion  of  thought 
to  many  of  those  who  are  induced  to  read  them,  but  also  because 
an  unmerited  importance  has  been  attached  to  them  by  a  section  of 
the  English  public,  misled  by  the  ingenious  and  systematic  advertise- 

*  Modern  Science  and  the  Illusions  of  Professor  Bergson.  By  Hugh  S.  R. 
Elliot  London,  Longmans  Green  &  Co.,  1912.  Price  $1.60  net. 


4OO  THE  MONIST. 

ment  of  M.  Bergson  by  those  who  amuse  themselves  with  metaphys- 
ical curiosities.  He  has  been  introduced  to  us  as  a  "great  French 
philosopher.'  To  those  who  in  a  thoroughgoing  way  occupy  them- 
selves in  collecting  and  comparing  and  classifying  all  the  absurdities 
which  have  been  put  forward  as  'metaphysics'  or  'metaphysical  specu- 
lation' since  the  days  of  Aristotle,  this  latest  effusion  has,  no  doubt,  a 
kind  of  interest  such  as  a  collector  may  take  in  a  curious  species  of 
beetle.  To  the  student  of  the  aberrations  and  monstrosities  of  the 
mind  of  man,  M.  Bergson's  works  will  always  be  documents  of 
value.  But  it  is  an  injustice  as  well  as  an  inaccuracy  to  speak  of 
their  author  as  'great,'  or  'French,'  or  a  'philosopher.'.  . .  . 

"A  main  objection  to  M.  Bergson's  account  of  his  own  per- 
formances in  the  dark  chamber  [of  the  metaphysical  x\  is  that  he 
is  not  content  with  asserting  (and  expecting  us  to  accept  his  bare 
assertion)  that  time  is  a  stuff  both  'resistant  and  substantial,'  that 
consciousness  is  not  always  dependent  on  cerebral  structure,  that  in- 
tuition is  a  true  guide  and  the  intellect  an  erroneous  guide.  Such 
escapades  in  the  dark  room  astonish  and  interest  only  those  who 
are  unacquainted  with  M.  Bergson's  numerous  predecessors  in  the 
maddening  hunt  of  the  illusive  black  cat.  It  is,  however,  a  speciality 
of  M.  Bergson  that  having  by  mere  assertion  attempted  to  make  us 
believe  that  he  has  grasped  the  black  cat,  and  at  any  rate  has  in 
his  hand  some  hairs  from  its  tail — he  proceeds  in  the  same  spirit 
to  make  absolutely  baseless  assertions  about  the  domain  of  scientific 
fact — a  domain  'tabooed'  against  him  and  his  fraternity.  He  writes 
of  the  facts  of  physical  science  with  the  same  careless  assurance  as 
that  which  we  tolerate  with  indifference  when  he  is  disporting  him- 
self in  the  extra-territorial  region  of  x.  Having  made  his  arbitrary 
assumptions  about  x,  he  proceeds  in  an  inaccurate  way  to  write  about 
some  of  the  well-ascertained  facts  of  the  structure  of  animals  and 
plants.  He  promulgates  novel  opinions  about  them  with  the  air  of 
one  who  has  given  serious  study  to  them,  which,  however,  it  is 
abundantly  evident  he  has  not.  By  a  light-hearted  perversion  of 
the  facts  as  to  the  structure  of  the  eyes  of  animals  and  other  such 
things,  he  endeavors  to  make  them  appear  as  evidence  in  support  of 
his  arbitrary  and  preposterous  fancies  about  x\  In  doing  so  he 
ceases  to  be  merely  an  amusing  juggler  with  the  harmless  creations 
of  his  own  and  other  people's  fancy:  he  becomes  a  maker  of  un- 
truth, and  for  those  who  listen  to  him  a  harmful  Confusionsmeister. 

"M.  Bergson  is  gifted  with  an  admirable  facility  of  diction,  and 
has  succeeded  in  arresting  attention.  On  that  account,  since  he 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  4OI 

has  exceeded  the  limits  of  fantastic  speculation  which  it  is  customary 
to  tolerate  on  the  stage  of  metaphysics,  and  has  carried  his  methods 
into  the  arena  of  sober  science,  it  is  a  matter  of  urgency  that  his  illu- 
sions and  perversions  should  be  exposed  with  uncompromising  frank- 
ness to  the  reading  public  who  may  be,  on  their  side,  under  an  illusion 
as  to  the  importance  of  his  teaching.  Mr.  Elliot's  book  effects  this 
exposure  in  a  masterly  way." 

M.  Bergson  proposes  the  strange  doctrine  that  perception  does 
not  reside  in  the  brain  of  the  perceiver,  but  in  the  object  perceived, 
— a  proposition  which  is  bewildering,  and  among  his  arguments  he 
declares  it  theoretically  not  inconceivable  that  matter  should  be  per- 
ceived without  sense  organs.  Such  doctrines  belong  to  the  corner- 
stone of  his  philosophy,  and  as  an  instance  of  Mr.  Elliot's  critique 
we  will  here  quote  some  paragraphs  discussing  M.  Bergson's  theory 
of  pain  and  of  memory.  M.  Bergson  defines  pain  as  an  "effort  to 
repair  damage."  Mr.  Elliot  writes: 

"Just  as  perception  is  located  in  the  perceived  object,  so  Berg- 
son alleges  that  pain  is  located  in  that  part  of  the  body  where  it 
appears  to  be  felt.  This  is  of  course  in  opposition  to  the  belief  of 
physiologists,  who  affirm  that  the  pain  is  really  located  in  the  brain, 
not  at  the  nerve  endings ;  and  who  support  their  contention  by  point- 
ing, for  instance,  to  the  pain  which  a  patient  feels  and  refers  to 
his  foot  after  it  has  for  years  been  amputated.  I  am  not,  however, 
concerned  to  defend  a  well-established  fact:  I  wish  only  to  point 
out  Bergson's  mode  of  refuting  it.  'If  [the  pain]  is  not  at  the 
point  where  it  appears  to  rise,  neither  can  it  be  anywhere  else:  if 
it  is  not  in  the  nerve,  neither  is  it  in  the  brain ;  for  to  explain  its 
projection  from  the  center  to  the  periphery  a  certain  force  is  neces- 
sary, which  must  be  attributed  to  a  consciousness  that  is  to  some 
extent  active.  Therefore,  he  must  go  further.  . .  .'  Here  we  get  a 
chain  of  deductions,  every  ling  of  which  appears  to  be  false.  Why 
should  any  force  be  necessary  ?  Why  should  that  force  be  attributed 
to  a  consciousness?  Why  should  that  consciousness  be  active?  It 
was  one  of  Huxley's  chief  gifts  to  biology  to  have  largely  banished 
deduction  from  that  science,  by  strongly  insisting  on  the  danger  of 
traveling  outside  ascertained  facts.  A  succession  of  deductions  like 
this,  in  a  physiological  inquiry,  is  a  priori  almost  certain  to  be 
erroneous.  To  me  a  posteriori  there  seems  not  even  prima  facie  evi- 
dence in  favor  of  any  of  them :  and  they  are  set  against  a  fact  ex- 
perimentally arrived  at! 

"The  doctrine  of  two  kinds  of  memory  is  a  complication  of 


4O2  THE   MONIST. 

natural  facts  that  will  not  appeal  to  anybody.  But  the  fundamental 
objection  to  it  is  that  so  often  raised  already :  that  there  are  no  facts 
to  support  it.  The  Professor  attacks  the  physiological  view  of  mem- 
ory :  he  adduces  a  number  of  facts,  such  as  those  of  sensory  aphasia, 
in  opposition  to  it ;  and  having  destroyed  it  to  his  own  satisfaction, 
forthwith  we  are  presented  with  a  new  theory  which  is  assumed  to 
be  true.  This  new  theory  is  worked  out  in  extreme  detail ;  it  is 
unaffected  by  sensory  aphasia,  but  otherwise  the  only  credentials  it 
can  produce  are  those  of  extreme  unintelligibility.  We  have  already 
had  occasion  to  observe  that  a  doctrine  is  safest  from  criticism  when 
it  is  most  difficult  to  understand.  The  fog  is  so  thick  that  the  critic 
is  disarmed.  I  therefore  make  no  specific  attack  upon  it,  beyond 
insisting  upon  the  complete  absence  of  evidence.  Moreover,  the 
attack  on  the  physiological  theory  could  scarcely  convince  ony  one 
but  a  metaphysician.  'If  memories  are  really  deposited  in  the  cortical 
cells,  we  should  find  in  sensory  aphasia  the  irreparable  loss  of  certain 
determined  words,  the  integral  conservation  of  others.'  But  it  is 
not  so.  Now,  what  would  a  man  of  science  consider  himself  entitled 
to  deduce  from  this  ?  Nothing  further  than  that  words  are  not 
represented  in  the  brain  in  minute  specific  areas  for  each  word,  but 
that  they  are,  or  may  be,  represented  in  some  other  way,  possibly 
still  undiscovered.  But  what  does  Bergson  infer?  That  the  mem- 
ories of  words  are  not  stored  in  the  brain  at  all.  He  refutes  a  crude 
physiological  hypothesis ;  he  then  assumes  that  the  refutation  applies 
to  all  possible  physiological  hypotheses,  and  thence  jumps  to  his 
own  theory.  It  would  have  been  just  as  reasonable  to  found  his 
own  theory  upon  a  refutation  of  Gall's  phrenology.  For  phrenology 
was  a  thoroughly  materialistic  hypothesis ;  it  assumed  absolute  con- 
nection between  mind  and  brain,  and  definite  localization  of  mental 
faculties  in  the  brain.  Phrenology  has  long  been  exploded,  but 
no  one  (except  a  metaphysician)  infers  from  that  that  there  is  no 
connection  between  mind  and  brain.  A  belief  in  that  connection  is 
in  no  wise  shaken  by  the  exposure  of  phrenology;  nor  is  it  shaken 
by  the  criticism  of  other  crude  attempts  to  localize  mental  qualities. 
These  criticisms  are  effective  only  for  the  particular  theories  against 
which  they  are  levelled.  Hence  we  see  that  Bergson's  theory  of 
mind  and  matter  is  founded  upon  the  same  fallacy  as  that  of  the 
vital  impetus — the  fallacy  which  we  stigmatized  as  the  mannikin 
fallacy  at  the  beginning  of  the  chapter.  In  bald  outline  it  is  like 
refuting  Mahommedanism,  and  then  arguing:  (1)  Mahommedan- 
ism  is  untrue;  (2)  therefore  all  religion  is  untrue;  (3)  therefore  all 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  403 

morality  is  a  superstition.  We  have  only  to  point  out  that  (2)  does 
not  follow  from  (1),  nor  does  (3)  follow  from  (2).  In  Bergson's 
works  the  second  step  (2)  is  invariably  taken  silently  immediately 

( 1 )  has  been  established.    The  great  show  of  facts  in  his  works  are 
all  connected  with  step  (1),  the  criticism  of  adverse  theories.    Step 

(2)  is  then  slurred  over  without  a  word  of  discussion,  and  the  rest 
of  the  philosophy  is  taken  up  with  step  (3),  which  is  just  a  hypoth- 
esis or  guess,  or  intuition,  having  no  connection  with   foregoing 
facts,  but  set  out  with  such  a  wealth  of  words  and  analogies  that 
the  unwary  reader  quickly  loses  his  way  and  is  totally  lost.     In 
alliance  with  the  main  paralogism  is  the  copious  misuse  of  analogies 
and  of  words,  the  latter  especially  in  the  form  of  materializing  ab- 
stractions such  as  time,  life,  motion,  memory.     The  medieval  real- 
ists could  scarcely  have  gone  farther. 

"The  tendency  to  attribute  substantial  reality  to  abstractions  is 
conspicuous  not  only  in  metaphysics  but  in  the  thinking  of  all  primi- 
tive races.  Thus  a  Basuto  will  not  walk  by  a  river  lest  his  shadow 
falling  on  the  water  should  be  seized  and  devoured  by  a  crocodile. 
Nearly  all  children  at  one  time  or  another  attempt  to  evade  their 
shadows  by  jumping  or  running.  Names  likewise  are  looked  upon 
as  material  things :  as  among  the  Chinooks,  one  of  whom  thought 
that  Kane's  desire  to  know  his  name  proceeded  from  a  wish  to  steal 
it.  Here,  as  elsewhere,  Bergson  does  nothing  more  than  systematize 
and  magnify,  on  an  enormous  scale,  almost  universal  vices  of 
thought." 

As  an  example  of  Bergson's  method  we  will  quote  a  few  more 
passages  from  Mr.  Elliot's  book.  Bergson  says: 

'  'Instinct  is  knowledge  at  a  distance.  It  has  the  same  rela- 
tion to  intelligence  that  vision  has  to  touch/  Why,  then,  do  we 
owe  our  knowledge  of  the  stars  to  intelligence,  and  not  to  instinct? 
Why  has  astronomy  advanced  by  the  gradual  triumph  of  intelligence 
over  bigoted  superstition  ? .  . .  . 

"Bergson's  attempt  to  establish  the  preeminence  of  men  and 
hymenoptera  takes,  in  one  place,  the  following  form: — 'It  is  un- 
questionable that  success  is  the  most  general  criterion  of  superiority, 
the  two  terms  being,  up  to  a  certain  point,  synonymous.  By  suc- 
cess must  be  understood,  so  far  as  the  living  being  is  concerned,  an 
aptitude  to  develop  in  the  most  diverse  environments  through  the 
greatest  possible  variety  of  obstacles  so  as  to  cover  the  widest  pos- 
sible extent  of  ground.  A  species  which  claims  the  entire  earth 
for  its  domain  is  truly  a  dominating  and,  consequently,  superior 


404  THE    MONIST. 

species.  Such  is  the  human  species,  which  represents  the  culminat- 
ing point  of  the  evolution  of  the  vertebrates.  But  such  also  are,  in 
the  series  of  the  articulate,  the  insects,  and,  in  particular,  certain 
Hymenoptera.  It  has  been  said  of  the  ants  that,  as  man  is  lord  of 
the  soil,  they  are  lords  of  the  subsoil.' 

"Under  this  definition,  birds  ought  to  be  a  dominating  group, 
for  their  distribution  is  wider  than  that  of  men.  And  the  most  pre- 
eminent species  of  all  would  not  be  men,  or  insects,  or  even  birds, 
but  those  simple  unicellular  creatures  like  ameba,  which  are  found 
everywhere  all  over  the  earth." 

Mr.  Elliot  sums  up  the  whole  book  with  the  following  con- 
clusion : 

"Professor  Bergson's  philosophy  is  contained  in  three  volumes. 
I  here  summarize  my  main  objection  to  the  fundamental  doctrine 
of  each: 

"1.    Time  is  a  stuff  both  'resistant  and  substantial.'     Where  is 

the  specimen  on  which  this  allegation  is  founded? 
"2.  Consciousness  is  to  some  extent  independent  of  cerebral 
structure.  Professor  Bergson  thinks  he  proves  this  by  dis- 
proving a  crude  theory  of  localization  of  mental  qualities. 
Will  he  furnish  evidence  of  its  existence  apart  from  cerebral 
structure  ? 

"3.  Instinct  leads  us  to  a  comprehension  of  life,  that  intellect 
could  never  give.  Will  Professor  Bergson  furnish  instances 
of  the  successes  of  instinct  in  biological  inquiries,  where 
intellect  has  failed? 

"I  venture  to  think  that,  until  these  questions  are  answered,  we 
are  not  called  upon  to  consider  further  the  merits  of  Professor  Berg- 
son's  philosophy."  EDITOR. 

KANT  AND  BERGSON.1 

"It  is  an  incorrect  and  perverted  usage  of  the  word 
'symbolic/  but  one  which  is  accepted  by  modern  logi- 
cians, when  it  is  set  in  opposition  to  the  'intuitive'  mode 
of  thought ;  for  the  symbolic  is  only  a  species  of  the 
intuitive." — Kant,  Critique  of  Judgment. 

We  have  in  Kant  not  only  the  founder  of  criticism  as  a  sys- 
tem or  a  method  which   would  be  appreciated   for  their  positive 
qualities ;  but  on  the  other  hand  the  purely  critical,  or  if  you  prefer 
negative,  element  is  for  the  most  part  considered  from  an  historical 
1  Translated  from  the  German  by  Lydia  G.  Robinson. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  405 

point  of  view  in  its  application  against  rationalism  and  against 
Locke  and  Hume.  At  bottom,  however,  Kant  himself  has  tire- 
lessly given  expression  to  the  propaedeutic  character  of  his  critique 
as  among  its  most  essential  features.  Therefore  it  seemed  to  him 
most  important  once  for  all  to  demonstrate  metaphysics,  as  he  found 
it  and  understood  it,  to  be  futile  and  impossible,  in  so  far  as  it  laid 
claim  to  being  a  system  of  cognitions. 

Whether  or  not  Kant  had  come  in  actual  contact  with  histor- 
ical metaphysics  alone  makes  no  difference.  He  undoubtedly  wished 
to  do  away  with  metaphysics  in  itself.  It  may  be  objected  that  he 
opposes  his  criticism  to  that  kind  of  metaphysics  which  he  himself 
has  constructed  as  the  object  of  attack.  Nevertheless  his  critique 
has  a  far  broader  application  inasmuch  as  it  makes  metaphysics  in 
general  the  object  of  investigation.  Whoever  maintains  the  mere 
possibility  of  a  metaphysics  must  in  some  way  or  other  decide  the 
question  which  Kant  himself  stated  and  wished  to  have  solved, 
namely  whether  metaphysics  is  at  all  possible. 

In  solving  this  problem  it  is  a  matter  of  indifference  whether  or 
not  one  employs  the  Kantian  method  of  deducing  the  possibility 
of  the  thing  sought  from  its  postulate,  from  the  hypothetical  as- 
sumptions of  the  problem.  Only  in  one  way  or  another  the  critical 
attitude  must  be  brought  to  bear  upon  the  question.  Hence  the 
nature  of  metaphysics  or  its  necessity  must  not  be  asserted  and 
presented  before  its  possibility  is  proved.  Therefore  it  is  really  im- 
possible for  a  Kantian  to  admit  the  methods  employed  by  Bergson 
in  founding  a  new  kind  of  metaphysics.  Nevertheless  we  shall  first 
accommodate  ourselves  to  his  mode  of  thought  so  that  we  can  not 
be  subject  to  the  charge  of  orthodox  critique.  Yes  we  will  even 
go  one  step  further.  We  will  hypothetically  admit  that  Bergson's 
definition  of  metaphysics  is  right.  He  asserts  metaphysics  to  be 
the  science  which  gets  along  without  symbols ;  it  is  intuitive  knowl- 
edge. 

According  to  Bergson  himself  intuition  is  a  sort  of  mental 
sympathy  by  means  of  which  one  may  transfer  himself  into  the 
midst  of  an  object.  Bergson  avails  himself  of  still  other  senses  in 
order  to  make  this  kind  of  cognition  comprehensible  to  us.  It  is  a 
kind  of  mental  auscultationp  an  intellectual  vision.  My  present  task 
is  to  investigate  whether  such  an  intuition  is  possible,  whether  it  is 
at  all  thinkable.  Bergson  is  satisfied  simply  to  make  the  assertion. 
But  I  will  first  show  that  even  granting  its  possibility  it  does  not 
accomplish  what  is  claimed  for  it. 


406  THE  MONIST. 

From  the  very  beginning  intuition  is  something  more  than 
merely  a  kind  of  cognition.  It  is  supposed  to  transfer  us  directly 
into  the  very  being  of  the  object,  but  in  this  being  is  included 
existence.  A  comprehension  of  existence  is  at  the  same  time  a 
comprehension  of  the  cause  of  existence.  The  play  is  ceaselessly 
repeated,  one  direct  leap  carries  us  across  the  abyss  of  cognition, 
perception  and  comprehension.  In  intuition  existence  itself  is  pos- 
ited. The  more  intuition  is  built  up  upon  being,  upon  existence, 
the  more  creative  and  the  more  constructive  does  it  itself  become. 
A  second  process,  that  of  deepening,  runs  parallel  to  this  develop- 
ment of  the  concept  of  intuition.  From  a  comprehension  of  the 
object,  from  a  sinking  into  a  strange  object,  from  a  constantly 
greater  pouring  out  of  the  subject,  intuition  becomes  more  and 
more  an  internal  process;  finally,  in  intuition  the  subject  comes 
more  and  more  to  comprehend  itself,  its  creative  nature,  its  most 
profound  existence. 

The  stages  of  this  development  are  well  known.  Scholasticism 
saw  in  intuition  the  cognition  of  existence  or  non-existence.  "In- 
tuitive knowledge  of  a  thing  is  knowledge  by  means  of  which  it  may 
be  known  whether  a  thing  is  or  is  not."2  The  logical  antithesis  of 
existence  and  non-existence  indicates  even  beyond  that  the  creative 
cause  of  existence.  It  is  only  necessary  for  the  factor  of  necessity 
to  be  abstracted  from  its  logical  wrappings  to  make  it  clear  that 
a  decision  about  existence  or  non-existence  ultimately  depends  on 
the  foundation,  the  positing  of  existence.  Existence  once  posited, 
the  cognition  of  its  necessity  is  at  the  same  time  admitted. 

Spinoza  goes  even  one  step  farther: 

"This  kind  of  knowledge,  i.  e.,  intuitive  knowledge,  proceeds 
from  an  adequate  idea  of  the  absolute  essence  of  certain  attributes 
of  God  to  the  adequate  knowledge  of  the  essence  of  things."3  By 
reference  to  God,  existence  is  therefore  established  more  securely 
so  that  the  scientia  intuitive?  latterly  comes  to  include  existence. 
Intuitive  knowledge  as  knowledge  under  the  form  of  eternity  com- 
prises this,  that  the  essentialities  of  things  follow  from  the  eternal 
nature  of  God  by  eternal  necessity.5  And  if  we  must  remove  the 

2  "Notitia  intuitiva  rei  est  talis  notitia,  virtute  cuius  potest  sciri,  utrum  res 
sit  vel  non  sit." — William  of  Occam,  in  /.  sent,  prooem. 

3  "Atque  hoc  cognoscendi  genus  (sc.  scientia  intuitiva')  procedit  ab  adae- 
quata  idea  essentiae,  formalis  quorundarum  Dei  attributorum  ad  adaequatam 
cognitionem  essentiae  rerum." — Ethices,  II,  Propos.  XL,  Schol.  2. 

4  Or  cognitio  intuitiva,  Eth.  V,  Prop.  36  Schol. 
*Eth.  V,  Prop.  25,  27,  and  Dem.  32. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  407 

factor  of  the  creative,  we  must  nevertheless  emphasize  with  Spinoza 
himself  the  power  and  the  force  of  this  third  step  in  cognition  from 
which  the  amor  intellectualis  del  arises. 

The  necessity  of  existence  in  the  scientia  intuitiva  can  not  be 
more  emphatically  expressed  than  in  the  words:  "Therefore  to 
conceive  things  under  the  form  of  eternity  is  to  conceive  things  in 
so  far  as  they  are  conceived  through  the  essence  of  God  as  real 
entities  or  insofar  as  they  involve  existence  through  the  essence  of 
of  God."6  The  climax  of  this  development  of  the  concept  of  intui- 
tion (Intuitionsbegriff)  is  Kant's  interpretation  of  the  nature  of 
intellectual  intuition  (Anschauung) .  According  to  him  it  is  a  non- 
sensual  active  "faculty"  which  produces  its  intuition  directly  and 
at  the  same  time  the  objects  of  that  intuition  by  its  spontaneous 
activity.  It  seems  that  Kant  saw  in  Plato's  Ideas  the  objective 
counterpart  of  this  intellectual  intuition,  for  in  them  as  intuitions 
a  priori  he  posits  the  primitive  cause  of  all  things.  ("Von  einem 
neuer  dings  erhobenen  vornehmen  Ton  in  d.  Philosophic,  Berliner 
Monatsschrift,  Mai,  1796.") 

Kant  shares  with  Spinoza  the  association  of  this  intellectual  in- 
tuition with  the  divine.  He  differs  from  him  in  that  he  does  not 
admit  with  Spinoza  that  it  is  possible  on  the  part  of  man. 

I  pass  over  entirely  the  concept  of  intuition  as  worked  out  in 
mysticism.  With  this  concept  the  intuition  of  Bergson  has  nothing 
to  do. 

Granted  that  intuition  is  possible,  what  does  it  accomplish?  It 
transfers  one  directly  into  the  midst  of  objects.  What  of  objectivity 
it  gains  it  loses  in  subjectivity.  Its  climax  is  its  coincidence  with 
the  essence  of  the  object,  and  thus  is  emphasized  as  something  quite 
distinct  from  it.  But  if  it  remains  distinct  then  it  must  always  be 
outside  of  the  center  of  the  object.  This  transference  into  a  strange 
object  is  really  only  a  purposeless  example  of  speculative  fancy,  for 
it  is  absolutely  inconceivable  how  a  subject  could  be  so  changed  into 
an  object  that  it  would  take  up  the  object  into  itself,  make  itself 
equivalent  to  it  and  yet  remain  autonomous  itself.  And  even  if  this 
procedure  were  possible  we  would  utterly  reject  the  dualistic  theory 
and  be  satisfied  with  the  admission  that  in  the  center  of  the  essence 
of  an  object  there  is  such  a  comprehension  of  this  center  that  exactly 
this  comprehension  would  always  be  meant  and  finally  would  be  so 

e"Res  igitur  sub  specie  aeternitatis  concipere  est  res  concipere,  quatenus 
per  Dei  essentiam  ut  entia  realia  concipiuntur  sive  quatenus  per  Dei  essentiam 
involvunt  existentiam." — Eth.  V,  Prop.  30,  Dem. 


408  THE  MONIST. 

understood  again,  provided  that  this  procedure  could  be  represented 
in  any  way. 

The  process  of  intuition  can  not  be  presented  nor  can  it  be  con- 
trolled. It  withdraws  from  every  attempt  at  presentation  or  control. 
In  secret  depths  there  suddenly  takes  place  an  escape,  a  /^ra/Jao-is  efc 
KpyiJUL  pursued  and  extended  indeed  with  effort  but  in  its  origin  and 
course  unknown  and  unknowable.  Means  are  entirely  lacking  to 
verify  its  necessity  and  validity  beyond  its  reality. 

Every  intuition  is  isolated,  yet  we  do  not  see  how  a  methodical 
and  systematic  connection  can  be  possible  in  the  sum  total  of  in- 
tuitions. Neither  an  ascent,  an  increasing  deepening,  a  methodical 
thought-action,  nor  a  well-constructed  systematic  connection  of  cog- 
nitions. But  we  might  perhaps  waive  this:  intuitions  crowd  to- 
gether in  one  of  the  most  important,  in  the  intuitive  attainment  of 
intuition  itself.  Thus  we  would  have  an  undivided  apex  crowning 
ihe  structure  of  cognition.  The  cognitions  themselves  might  be  of 
another  kind.  But  when  and  in  whom  is  this  intuition  to  take  place  ? 
Can  any  one  attain  it  at  any  time  by  making  sufficient  effort  and 
striving  to  win  it?  If  so,  I  should  think  that  exactly  these  prelim- 
inary conditions,  the  knowledge  of  the  kind  of  our  endeavors,  would 
greatly  concern  us,  and  intuition  itself  would  let  our  endeavor  fall 
from  us  void  of  interest  like  ripe  fruit.  There  is  something  infinitely 
wearisome  about  intuition.  At  one  stroke  it  tears  away  the  veil 
from  the  mystery  of  mysteries  and  then  all  work  is  performed  for- 
ever. And  yet  not  for  ever.  It  remains  finally,  to  be  sure,  the 
possession  of  its  acquirer  who  is  not  in  a  condition  to  communicate 
it  to  others  though  he  can  indeed  arrange  to  put  himself  in  pos- 
session of  it,  but  has  the  possession  for  himself  without  being  able 
to  compare  it  or  to  communicate  it.  So  from  this  point  weighty 
prospects  open  before  us.  We  do  not  exactly  see  how  intuition  could 
remain  as  a  possession  with  its  acquirer.  He  must  ever  seek  to 
acquire  it  anew,  for  in  memory  exactly  that  disappears  which  makes 
it  intuition,  namely,  the  lack  of  the  symbolic,  an  everlasting  coming 
and  going  of  intuitive  experiences  without  plan  or  method,  without 
connection  or  aim.  For  each  one  brings  with  it  as  the  supreme 
purpose  of  cognition,  but  only  as  an  experience,  the  truth  as  it  is 
given,  not  as  it  is  known,  comprehended  and  perceived. 

However,  the  deeper  we  descend  into  the  inwardness  of  the  sub- 
ject which  produces  the  intuition,  the  stronger  is  evidenced  the  char- 
acteristic note  of  the  personal  life,  and  the  more  distinct  becomes 
the  absolute  in  itself.  Assuming  too  that  we  include  in  these  depths 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  409 

the  real,  the  cosmical  center  of  the  spiritual  life,  then  exactly  this 
personal  element,  this  experience,  gives  it  a  particularly  independent 
garb.  From  this  point  it  is  quite  unimaginable  how  being  and 
experience  are  to  be  associated  together.  The  best  we  can  do  is  to 
assert  that  the  Kantian  problem  of  cognition  becomes  deepened  and 
broadened  but  it  goes  no  further.  Intuition,  too,  whose  legal  char- 
acter and  validity  must  be  comprehended  or  intuitively  perceived, 
is  not  a  datum  or  a  reality;  but  it  is  a  problem  and  one  that  has 
validity. 

What  importance  for  intuition  has  the  character  of  truth  ?  Since 
it  can  not  be  determined  either  categorically  or  by  means  of  ideas 
and  especially  not  by  symbols,  it  can,  to  be  sure,  contain  truth  in 
itself — yes,  according  to  its  concept  it  must  contain  truth;  but  how 
and  by  what  intrinsic  necessity  it  contains  truth  can  by  no  means  be 
expressed  without  symbols.  Only  no  one  needs  to  know  that  a 
cognition  or  an  experience  contains  truth  (for  this  knowledge  would 
be  either  accidental  or  problematic)  but  only  to  know  by  what  neces- 
sity truth  is  bound  to  a  cognition  or  an  experience.  Then  too  the 
mere  possession  of  truth  is  worthless  so  long  as  it  is  not  known  that 
it  has  its  roots  in  well-grounded  associations. 

Therefore  intuition  must  be  rejected  as  a  postulate  because  it 
cannot  serve  to  give  any  one  an  accidental  experience  of  finding 
himself  in  the  center  of  an  object.  The  primeval  dream  of  humanity 
to  be  able  to  know  finality,  to  be  able  to  possess  everything,  to 
penetrate  into  the  innermost  kernel  of  things,  is  in  itself  contra- 
dictory and  untenable.  Of  what  use  is  it  to  me  to  be  in  the  center 
of  an  object  if  I  do  not  have  besides  an  intuition  that  this  is  the 
case,  that  it  actually  is  the  case?  Did  not  Descartes  remind  us  of 
the  possibility  that  a  conception  could  be  produced  in  us  arbitrarily 
and  delusively  from  an  outside  cause?  He  comes  to  the  conclusion 
that  our  fancy  can  actually  transport  us  into  a  foreign  object  very 
vividly  and  naturally  without  question,  and  yet  with  an  easy  effort 
if  not  simultaneously  we  can  have  the  consciousness  that  it  was 
simply  an  image  of  our  fancy.  In  the  moment  when  I  by  means  of 
certain  efforts  of  the  imagination  live  in  a  vividly  portrayed  char- 
acter of  romance  I  have  nothing  but  this  imaginative  figure  within 
me  and  it  is  utterly  impossible  for  me  to  accompany  this  process, 
which  likewise  is  reflected  in  the  very  threshold  of  consciousness, 
with  a  particular  act  of  consciousness  which  includes  it  as  object 
or  even  only  with  the  mere  idea  of  the  ego.  On  the  other  hand  it 


4IO  THE  MONIST. 


is  ye*y  possible  to  emphasize  and  to  comprehend  an  act  of  imagina- 
tion in  a  particular  process  of  consciousness. 

Accordingly  since  intuition  is  said  to  transfer  one  directly  into 
an  object,  this  is  analogous  to  throwing  a  piece  of  sugar  into  water. 
The  sugar  is  dissolved  ;  "it"  is  indeed  in  the  water,  but  the  "piece" 
of  sugar  is  not  in  it. 

Intuition  is  a  sort  of  absolute  cognition.  If  intuition  is  possible, 
if  we  could  penetrate  at  even  one  point  into  the  mystery  of  the 
universe,  the  force  of  our  cognition  would  be  weakened  forever 
at  this  point.  At  the  most  we  would  still  have  to  assert  and  com- 
municate the  endeavor  and  the  achievement  if  we  could  —  at  best 
the  old  traditionalism  of  the  end  of  the  eighteenth  century.  How- 
ever, it  is  clear  that  intuition  has  already  its  results  in  great  men, 
exceptional  personalities,  and  that  definite  institutions  or  school 
buildings  had  them  in  charge.  Then  the  incessant  effort  to  attain 
possession  of  these  intuitions  would  always  be  simply  in  order  to 
gain  the  same  possession.  Of  course  Bergson  himself  does  not  in- 
tend this,  but  it  is  implied  in  the  consequence  of  this  wearisome 
intuition. 

Bergson  has  foreseen  the  dangers  that  threaten,  for  instance, 
his  concept  of  intuition.  He  constantly  asserts  the  activity  of  in- 
tuition. There  is  no  doubt  that  such  an  exceptional  event  as  attain- 
ing the  absolute  is  accompanied  and  introduced  by  attempts  and 
efforts  of  an  extremely  energetic  kind.  But  intuition  itself  is  not 
for  this  reason  active  in  any  sense,  although  it  is  accompanied  by 
activity.  Exactly  the  last  point,  namely  transference,  in  which  the 
absolute  and  the  comprehending  subject  almost  coincide,  must  also 
stand  on  the  lowest  step  of  activity,  otherwise  the  whole  process  of 
identity  would  be  incomprehensible. 

Bergson  will  undoubtedly  accuse  every  critic  of  trying  to  assail 
his  concept  of  "pure"  intuition  with  symbols  in  an  inadmissible  way. 
But  what  if  the  gift  of  intuition  refuses  to  come  to  us  in  spite  of  all 
our  efforts?  Then  in  Bergson's  estimation  we  are  indubitably  lost 
as  metaphysicians.  It  seems  to  me  that  the  appeal  to  intuition  would 
greatly  resemble  the  appeal  to  the  healthy  human  understanding 
which  Bergson  to  be  sure  also  invokes  (p.  40).  But  Bergson  must 
show  us  distinctly  and  precisely  the  ways  and  means  that  lead  to 
intuition. 

The  intellectual  experience  (Miterleben)  of  the  real  mobility 
by  which  thinking  is  obliged  constantly  to  reverse  the  work  of 
thought,  is  claimed  to  be  accomplished  methodically.  Or,  rather, 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  411 

only  the  reversion  is  properly  claimed  to  be  performed  methodically. 
For  does  not  Bergson  see  that  we  are -again  under  the  spell  of  the 
formulism  of  symbols  which  has  just  been  rejected  with  the  greatest 
energy?  Are  not  mobility,  reversion  and  method  symbols  just  as 
much  as  cognition,  validity,  categories,  etc.?  Bergson  himself  sees 
how  difficult  it  is  for  "the  intuition  once  attained  to  find  a  mode  of 
expression  and  application  corresponding  to  our  habits  of  thought 
and  offering  us  in  firmly  postulated  concepts  the  secure  supports  of 
which  we  are  so  in  need." 

But  everything  finally  comes  to  this,  that  if  one  were  constantly 
to  imagine  that  he  could  transfer  himself  directly  into  the  midst  of 
an  object  by  exerting  a  special  energy,  this  procedure  would  remain 
epistemologically  and  metaphysically  valueless  so  long  as  it  does 
not  succeed  in  establishing  the  scope  and  degree  of  its  validity,  its 
internal  truthfulness,  the  origin  and  structure  of  its  composition,  etc. 
It  never  depends  on  the  cognition  or  experience  in  itself,  nor  on  its 
kind  which  may  be  described  as  much  as  one  wishes,  but  always  on 
laying  the  foundation  of  cognition  on  a  firm  interrelation.  Upon 
what  is  the  certainty  of  an  intuition,  and  necessarily  of  its  contents, 
based?  In  what  consists  the  security  that  I  actually  grasp  the  es- 
sence of  a  thing,  that  I  really  am  in  the  center  of  the  object? 

Bergson  thinks  he  possesses  one  means  of  comparison.  He  is 
convinced  that  the  consciousness  we  have  of  our  own  person  in  its 
"continuous  course  leads  us  into  the  interior  of  one  reality  after 
whose  pattern  we  must  construct  the  rest." 

He  also  upsets  Kant's  theory  of  the  unknowability  of  the  ego. 
....  "Accordingly  I  have  no  knowledge  of  myself,  what  I  am,  but 
merely  how  I  appear  to  myself."7 

We  nowhere  find  in  Bergson  any  attempt  formally  to  oppose 
the  well-known  deductions  of  Kant.  At  the  same  time  he  arms 
himself  against  Kant's  proofs.  He  accuses  Kant  of  "misconstruing 
the  union  of  the  sciences  and  metaphysics  with  intellectual  in- 
tuition." It  would  have  been  more  correct  to  say  that  Kant  has 
opposed  it  with  all  his  energy.  Kant  did  not  in  the  least  accuse 
metaphysics  of  being  empty  speculation;  he  was  even  the  first  to 
point  out  the  necessity  of  the  metaphysical  impulse.  But  he  has 
undertaken  to  show  that  metaphysics  could  never  stand  as  a  system 
of  cognitions.  His  problem  was  formulated :  Is  metaphysics  every- 
where possible  as  a  unity  of  cognition?  and  his  answer  was  firm 

1 Cr.  of  Pure  Reason,  II,  p.  157,  cf.  135,  399  ff.,  and  also  the  alteration  of 
the  first  edition.    Proleg.,  136  ff. 


412  THE  MONIST. 

and  decided,  Not  at  all.  With  equal  energy  he  rejected  intellectual 
intuition  as  cognition.  Whoever  makes  both  assertions  repeatedly 
is  obliged  to  shatter  and  overturn  Kant's  critique  in  its  fundamentals. 

But  this  is  not  the  case  since  Natorp's  and  Cohen's  system  has 
been  called  a  "dream"  (p.  52).  Ultimately  we  will  have  to  dispose 
of  the  idea  which  ascribes  to  Kant  such  a  dogmatism  as  even  his 
own  opponents  have  not  consistently  perfected,  which  maintains  that 
after  Kant  "the  main  task  of  criticism  is  to  determine  what  the 
intellect  is  supposed  to  be  and  what  the  object"  (p.  52).  Equally 
dogmatic  is  the  postulate  that  is  ascribed  to  Kant  that  the  intellect 
is  incapable  of  doing  anything  but  "Platonize,  i.  e.,  cast  every  pos- 
sible experience  into  previously  existing  moulds"  (p.  53). 

To  be  sure  we  are  no  longer  satisfied  with  the  conception  of 
metaphysics  as  it  appeared  to  Kant.  Likewise  is  it  far  indeed  from 
us  absolutely  to  deny  its  possibility  as  he  did.  We  maintain  that 
greater  depths  of  the  soul,  which  Kant  also  divined  (synthetic  one- 
ness of  apperception)  can  become  present  to  us,  but  not  by  the  help 
of  intuition,  of  intellectual  perception  (Anschauung) ,  but  in  an 
energetic  apprehension,  in  an  active  realization  of  its  infinite  con- 
tent. Hence  we  consciously  abandon  cognition  and  its  ways  and 
means  which  Bergson  desires  to  broaden  and  deepen  anew.  For 
by  means  of  intellectual  perception  we  fall  again  and  still  deeper 
into  the  miserable  intellectualism  in  which  we  long  enough  have 
lain  imprisoned. 

Intuition  indeed  is  to  be  divested  of  all  intellectuality.  Apart 
from  the  fact  that  it  thus  incurs  the  loss  of  all  power  of  cognition, 
it  becomes  in  addition  a  kind  of  assimilation  of  the  object  which 
repeats  in  some  way  or  other  its  content,  and  is  everything  else,  ex- 
cept cognition  or  comprehension.  And  yet  finally  the  resultant,  the 
sum  total  of  the  intuitive  performance  must  be  analogous  to  "ex- 
perience." The  bare  object  must  be  distinguished  from  the  object 
in  the  confusion  of  intuition.  And  right  here  lies  the  problem.  For 
that  an  object  can  be  concerned  with  intuition  would  be  possible 
in  itself.  But  who  could  undertake  to  find  out  by  any  other  means 
than  through  intuition  what  the  characteristic  feature  of  the  object 
is,  and  on  the  other  hand  the  content  of  the  perfected  intuition? 

Assuming  the  possibility  of  intuition,  it  does  not  accomplish 
what  is  claimed  for  it.  The  leap  into  the  thing  buries  the  one  who 
takes  it.  Intuition  assumes  a  thing  which  outside  of  and  independ- 
ent of  itself  does  not  exist.  Intuition  is  not  only  unfruitful,  it  is  even 
impossible. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  413 

For  this  statement  I  hope  to  bring  forward  convincing  proofs. 
All  the  varied  results  and  evolutions  of  modern  epistemology  pos- 
sess the  common  feature  of  interpreting  cognition  as  complete  and 
immanent.  It  deduces  all  single  factors  and  elements  from  the 
problems  and  laws  of  cognition  itself  but  does  not  construct  them 
a  priori  upon  metaphysical  foundations.  For  although  the  con- 
stitutive features  of  the  nature  of  cognition  might  be  based  on 
metaphysical  relations  yet  that  which  makes  cognition  cognition 
can  be  ascertained  only  by  their  surrender.  Hence  a  kind  of 
cognition  which  assumes  the  "thing"  as  given  according  to  its  ex- 
istence and  its  nature  is  self-contradictory.  Cognition  exactly  im- 
plies that  it  gains,  attains,  performs  something.  A  mere  trans- 
migration into  the  center  would  either  signify  a  mere  presence  in 
the  thing  or  a  replacement  of  the  objective  central  point  by  an 
assimilating  subject.  In  either  case  no  decision  is  reached  about 
cognition  itself. 

The  tendency  of  modern  epistemology  is  to  look  upon  every- 
thing as  under  the  law  of  cognition.  Bergson  tries  to  push  the  thing, 
the  ''inwardness"  (Inncrc)  of  cognition,  before  it  and  place  it  out- 
side. Moreover  the  "being  in  the  center"  is  the  characteristic  fea- 
ture of  cognition.  But  while  Bergson  stops  here  the  modern  epis- 
temologists  begin  to  lay  their  foundation  at  just  this  point.  The 
method  by  which  the  center  of  the  object  is  reached  is  most  im- 
portant. That  cognition  reaches  this  point  is  implied  in  its  concept 
and  need  not  be  so  greatly  emphasized.  But  how  it  attains  it  is 
important,  and  it  makes  the  matter  rather  easy  if  the  proper  cognitive 
process  in  the  mysterious  leap  into  the  center  is  allowed  to  plunge 
undiscerned.  The  problem  is  not  how  one  can  be  "in"  a  thing,  but 
how  in  this  center  he  can  be  active,  and  of  what  kind  is  the  assimi- 
lation or  establishment  of  the  center. 

Then  too  the  idea  of  a  "central  point"  is  an  uncertain  one 
because  it  makes  the  end  disappear  and  yet  holds  fast  to  the  goal 
even  though  undetermined.  Thus  the  methodical  character  of  cog- 
nition is  entirely  overlooked,  and  its  infinite  exertion  does  not  come 
to  its  own. 

The  interrelated  cosmos  of  the  objects  of  cognition  is  knocked 
into  nothing,  and  is  firmly  bound  to  unchangeable  points.  Intuition 
wills  everything  and  is  itself  nothing. 

However  greatly  much  in  Bergson's  work  appeals  to  us,  espe- 
cially the  significance  of  the  real  as  something  moveable  (although 
the  last  word  does  not  seem  to  have  been  spoken  even  here),  yet 


414  THE  MONIST. 

we  must  take  issue  as  energetically  against  the  theory  of  intuition 
as  against  his  pragmatism  (page  54). 

I  have  not  formulated  the  above  considerations  systematically 
but  have  rather  adopted  the  rhetorical  style  of  the  French  in  order 
to  remain  as  objective  as  possible.  It  seems  to  me  the  time  has 
riot  yet  come  for  a  far-reaching  reflective  critique,  since  Bergson 
has  promised  a  more  conclusive  argument  for  his  theory  in  the 
future.  In  any  case  he  must  without  question  come  to  an  under- 
standing with  Kant;  for  to  uphold  metaphysics  according  to  Kant 
is  difficult,  but  to  introduce  intuition  again  is  by  far  the  most  diffi- 
cult. 

DR.  BRUNO  JORDAN. 

EINBECK,  GERMANY. 


MAUPERTUIS  AND  THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  LEAST  ACTION. 

The  present  investigations  are  concerned  with  the  history  of  the 
Principle  of  Least  Action  in  the  hands  of  Maupertuis,  Euler  and 
others.  The  subject  is  of  great  importance  in  the  history  of  mechan- 
ics, both  because  the  principle  of  least  action  became,  in  the  hands 
of  Lagrance,  "the  mother,"  as  Jacobi  expressed  it,  "of  our  analytical 
mechanics,"  and  because  the  animistic  tendency  displayed  in  the 
search  for  a  maximum  or  a  minimum  principle  in  physics  undoubt- 
edly had  a  great  influence  on  such  moulders  of  mechanical  theory  as 
Euler,  Lagrange  (in  his  early  work).1  Hamilton,  Gauss,  and,  in 

1  Besides  Lagrange's  early  printed  works,  his  correspondence  with  Euler 
allows  us  to  form  some  impression  of  the  stimulating  effect  which  the  principle 
of  least  action  had  on  Lagrange's  mind  at  the  beginning  of  his  career.  La- 
grange's  correspondence  with  Euler  extends  from  1754  (probably:  the  year 
is  not  given)  to  1775  and  is  reproduced  in  the  CEuvres  de  Lagrange,  vol.  xiv, 
pp.  133-245.  Already  in  1754  Lagrange  announces  (ibid.,  p.  138)  that  he 
has  made  "some  observations  about  the  maxima  and  minima  which  are  in 
the  actions  of  nature."  In  a  letter  of  August  12,  1755  (ibid.,  pp.  138-139)  La- 
grange  informs  Euler  that  he  had  a  new  and  simpler  method  of  solving  iso- 
perimetrical  problems  and  (ibid.,  pp.  140-144)  gives  a  full  statement  of  it 
(cf.  Euler's  reply,  ibid.,  pp.  144-146).  This  discovery  of  what  was  afterwards 
called  "the  calculus  of  variations"  certainly  gave  the  principle  of  least  action 
an  additional  attractiveness  to  Lagrange ;  he  speaks,  in  a  letter  of  May  19, 
J756,  of  his  meditations  "on  the  application  of  the  principle  of  least  action  to 
the  whole  of  dynamics"  (ibid.,  p.  155 ;  cf.  pp.  156,  158,  161,  and  the  final  sen- 
tences of  Lagrange's  first  printed  paper  in  the  first  volume  of  his  CEuvres}. 
Lagrange's  interest  in  the  principle  of  least  action  seems  to  have  evaporated 
when  he  observed  that,  when  developed,  the  integrand  is  the  variational  form 
of  d'Alembert's  principle,  and  that  it  is  simpler  and  equally  effective  to  start 
with  the  equations  of  motion  divorced  from  the  integration.  This  is  La- 
grange's  point  of  view  in  1788.  The  earliest  date  at  which  this  change  in 
point  of  view  is  shown  is,  so  far  as  I  can  find,  1764  (early  memoir  on  the 
libration  of  the  moon).  In  a  letter  of  Sept.  15,  1782,  to  Laplace,  Lagrange 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  415 

our  own  times,  Willard  Gibbs.  I  have  avoided,  as  much  as  possible, 
entering  into  merely  biographical  details  and  details  of  the  great 
controversy  between  Maupertuis,  Konig,  Euler,  and  Voltaire  about 
this  very  principle,  in  so  far  as  they  have  no  value  in  the  history  of 
science.  But  I  have  been  very  careful  to  give  accurate  and  detailed 
references  to  the  books  and  memoirs  where  everything  relevant,  so 
far  as  I  know,  may  be  found.  I  mention  this  expressly,  because 
much  in  this  chapter  of  the  evolution  of  mechanics — one  may  even 
say,  of  thought  in  general — has  been  misquoted  or  misunderstood 
by  even  eminent  authorities.  Unless  the  contrary  is  stated,  all  the 
books  referred  to  have  been  consulted  either  by  my  assistant,  Miss 
Harwood,  or  by  myself.2 


Pierre  Louis  Moreau  de  Maupertuis^  was  born  at  Saint-Malo  in 
1698  and  died  at  Basel  in  1759.  He  was  the  first  French  New- 
tonian ;4  was  the  author  of  several  papers  on  the  figure  of  the  earth 
and  the  leader  of  that  well-known  French  expedition  which  meas- 
ured an  arc  of  the  meridian  in  Lapland,  confirming  the  deduction 
from  the  Newtonian  theory  that  the  earth  is  flatter  at  the  poles  ;5 

says  ((Euvres,  vol.  xiv.,  p.  116)  that  he  has  almost  finished  a  mechanical 
treatise  uniquely  founded  on  "the  principle  or  formula"  given  in  section  i  of 
his  memoir  of  1780  on  the  libration  of  the  moon. 

2  Adolf  Mayer  (Geschichte  des  Princips  der  kleinsten  Action.  Akademische 
Antrittsvorlesung,  Leipsic,  1877,  p.  7)  reports  that  among  the  manuscripts  left 
by  Jacobi  are  fragments  of  a  history  of  the  principle  of  least  action  of  which 
he  has  made  use. 

3  There  is  a  biography  of  Maupertuis  by  La  Beaumelle  {Vie  de  Maupertuis 
par  L.  Angliviel  de  la  Beaumelle;  ouyrage  posthume,  suivi  de  lettres  inedites 
de  Frederic  le  Grand  et  de  Maupertuis,  avec  des  notes  et  un  appendice,  Paris, 
1856).     Cf.  also  Samuel  Formey,  Eloge  de  M.  de  Maupertuis  (read  in  1760), 
reprinted,  with  additions  and  corrections  by  de  la  Condamine  and  Trublet,  in 
1766  in  the  Histoire  de  V Academic  de  Berlin  for  1759,  pp.  464-512;  and  Emil 

du  Bois-Reymond,  Maupertuis;  Rede ,  Leipsic,  1893   (on  La  Beaumelle' s 

book,  see  pp.  72-81). 

4  La  Beaumelle,  op.  cit.,  p.  16;    du  Bois-Reymond,  op.  cit.,  pp.  17-18.    See 
Maupertuis's  papers  in  the  Paris  Memoires  for  1732-1736;  and  Discours  sur 
les  differentes  figures  des  astres,  'avec  une  exposition  des  systemes  de  MM. 
Descartes  et  Newton,  published  anonymously  at  Paris  in  1732  and  again  in  1742 
(not  seen),  and  the  popular  part  of  it  is  most  conveniently  consulted  in  the 
(Euvres  de  Mr.  de  Maupertuis,  Lyons,  1756,  vol.  i,  pp.  79-170.     Cf.  La  Beau- 
melle, op.  cit.,  pp.  23-34;  I.  Todhunter,  A  History  of  the  Mathematical  The- 
ories of  Attraction  and  the  Figure  of  the  Earth  from  the  Time  of  Newton  to 
that  of  Laplace,  London,  1873,  vol.  i,  pp.  63-76,  93-102  (this  also  contains  an 
account  of  those  works  which  come  into  the  scope  of  the  next  note). 

5  La  Beaumelle,  op.  cit.,  pp.  34-64,  71-75,  457-458,  461-462,  467;  Du  Bois- 
Reymond,  op.  cit.,  pp.  18-35;  and  a  German  translation  with  notes  by  myself, 
of  Clairaut's  book  of  1743  on  the  figure  of  the  earth,  which  is  soon  to  appear 
in  Ostwald's  Klassiker. 


4l6  THE  MONIST. 

and  was  Frederick  the  Great's  President  of  the  Berlin  Academy6 
(from  1746).  With  Maupertuis's  geometrical  works  we  are  not 
concerned  here/  nor  are  we  with  those  philological  and  anatomical 
speculations  of  his,  which  were  so  ruthlessly  and  unjustly  parodied 
by  Voltaire. 

According  to  Du  Bois-Reymond,8  Maupertuis's  teleological  ten- 
dencies showed  themselves  early  in  his  career  in  speculations  as  to 
what  grounds  the  Creator  could  have  had  for  preferring  the  law  of 
the  inverse  square  to  all  other  possible  laws  of  attraction. 

Some  words  about  Maupertuis's  personal  character  are  neces- 
sary. When  Maupertuis  returned  from  Lapland,  there  was  great 
opposition  in  some  quarters  to  the  reception  of  his  results.  This 
foolish  opposition  had  a  bad  influence  on  Maupertuis :  his  never  small 
feeling  of  self-importance  increased,  and  he  became  embittered.9  On 
the  other  hand,  he  was  given,  as  President  of  the  Berlin  Academy, 
almost  unlimited  powers,  even  as  regards  the  payment  of  the  mem- 
bers' pensions,10  and  this  may  partly  explain,  as  Carlyle  suggests 
in  his  Frederick  the  Great,  the  tiring  chorus  of  praise  that  breaks 
out  in  the  Berlin  Histoire  whenever  any  of  the  members  have  occa- 
sion to  mention  Maupertuis's  name.  In  the  course  of  our  discussions, 
too,  we  shall  have,  in  order  to  correct  a  strange  error  about  Mau- 
pertuis and  the  principle  of  least  action  made  by  Lord  Morley  in  his 
well-known  book  on  Diderot  and  the  Encyclopedists,  to  touch  upon 
the  question  as  to  whether  Maupertuis  was  a  materialist  or  not." 

ii. 

Maupertuis  read  to  the  Paris  Academy  on  the  20th  of  February, 
1740,  a  memoir  entitled:  "Loi  du  Repos  des  Corps."12  He  began 
by  remarking  that  demonstrations  a  priori  of  such  principles  as  that 

6  La  Beaumelle,  op.  cit.,  pp.  65-68,  76,  91-98,  104;  du  Bois-Reymond,  op. 
cit.,  pp.  36,  38,  39-42. 

7  La   Beaumelle,   op.   cit.,  pp.    15-16.    18-19,  22-23,  460-461 ;   du   Bois-Rey- 
mond, op.  cit.,  p.  16 ;  M.  Cantor,  Vorlesungen  iiber  Geschichte  der  Mathematik, 
vol.  iii,  2d  ed.,  Leipsic,  1901,  pp.  774-775,  786. 

8  Op.  cit.,  p.  18.    The  place  where  this  speculation  is  given  is  in  the  Figure 
des  Astres  ((Euvres,  1756,  vol.  i,  pp.  166-170). 

9  Du  Bois-Reymond,  op.  cit.,  p.  33. 

10  Ibid.,  p.  40 ;  La  Beaumelle,  op.  cit.,  p.  107. 

11  In  the  course  of  this  article,  we  shall  refer  to  Mach's  work  on  mechanics 
as  Mechanik  and  Mechanics,  as  we  have  done  before  (Monist,  April,  1912). 

12  Histoire   de   I 'Academic   royale   des  sciences.     Annee   1740.     Avec   les 
Memoires  de  Math,  et  de  Phys.  pour  la  meme  Annee,  Paris,  1742,  pp.  170-176; 
(Euvres,  1756,  vol.  iv,  pp.  45-63. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  417 

of  the  conservation  of  vis  viva  "cannot  apparently  be  given  by  phys- 
ics ;  they  seem  to  belong  to  some  higher  science." 

Maupertuis  sought  for  a  general  law  in  statics  analogous  to 
the  known  theorem  that,  in  any  system  of  elastic  bodies  in  motion, 
which  act  upon  one  another,  ^m.v'2  is  constant,  and  found  that:  In 
order  that  a  system  of  bodies  of  which  each  is  attracted  to  a  center 
by  a  force  varying  as  the  nth  power  of  the  distance  from  that  center, 
should  remain  in  equilibrium,  it  is  necessary  that 

Sw./.s"41, 

where  /  is  the  intensity  of  the  force  which  acts  on  m,  and  z  is  the 
distance  of  the  mass  m  from  its  center  of  force,  is  a  maximum  or  a 
minimum.  In  the  proof,  by  showing  the  truth  of  the  principle  in 
two  classes  of  cases,  he  concludes  that  as,  for  equilibrium 

Si«./.s*.<fcr=;0j 
the  above  sum  must  be  a  maximum  or  a  minimum.1 3 

In  an  "Addition"  added  to  the  reprint  in  the  (Euvrcs,14  Mau- 
pertuis remarked  that  his  law  holds  if  the  forces  are  proportional 
to  functions  Z  of  the  distances  £,  and  then  the  law  is  that 

Sw././Z.cte 
must  be  a  minimum.15 

in. 

Mattpertuis's  first  enunciation  of  the  law  of  the  least  quantity 
of  action  was  in  a  memoir  read  to  the  French  Academy  on  April 
15th,  1744,  entitled:  "Accord  de  differentes  Loix  de  la  Nature  qui 
avoient  jusqu'ici  paru  incompatibles."16  The  laws  in  question  ap- 

13  If  there  is  one  constant  force  on  all  the  masses,  and  its  center  is  at  an 
infinite  distance  from  the  system,  the  center  of  gravity  of  the  system  must  be 
as  far  as  possible  from,  or  as  near  as  possible  to,  this  center,  for  equilibrium  to 
subsist. 

14  Vol.  iv,  pp.  62-63.    It  should  be  remarked  that  Euler,  in  a  paper  quoted 
below  in  the  Berlin  Histoire  for  1751,  pp.  171-173,  had  pointed  out:  (i)  that  it 
is  not  necessary  that  the  forces  are  proportional  to  like  powers  of  the  dis- 
tances, provided  that  we  do  not  neglect  the  coefficients  i/(n+i)  when  they  are 
different  for  the  different  bodies  on  which  the  forces  act  (p.  171)  ;   (2)   that 
the  forces  need  not  be  supposed  to  be  proportional  to  functions    (f auctions 
quelconques)  of  the  distances,  and  if  the  force  is  V  instead  of  fsn,  Zf.m.V.ds 
will  then  be  a  maximum  or  a  minimum — according  to  the  kind  of  equilibrium 
(p.  172)  ;  and  (3)  that  the  whole  distance  of  each  body  from  the  centers  of 
forces  need  not  be  considered,  but,  if  convenience  of  calculation  requires  it, 
we  need  only  consider  the  distances  of  the  bodies  from  fixed  points  on  the 
lines  of  direction  of  the  forces  (pp.  172-173). 

15  Maupertuis  does  not  add:  "or  a  maximum."    The  subject  of  this  memoir 
of  1740  and  its  connection  with  the  principle  of  least  action  were  afterwards 
greatly  developed  by  Euler.    Cf.  also  Mach,  Mechanik,  pp.  69-75;  Mechanics, 
pp.  68-73. 

16 Histoire  de  I' Academic;  Annee  1744  (Paris,  1748),  pp.  417-426;  CEuvres, 
1756,  vol.  iv,  pp.  3-18  (with  the  addition  referred  to  below). 


4l8  THE  MONIST. 

pear1?  to  be  those  of  the  reflection  and  of  the  refraction  of  light. 
When  a  ray  of  light  in  a  uniform  medium  travels  from  one  point 
to  another,  either  without  meeting  an  obstacle  or  with  meeting  a 
reflecting  surface,  nature  leads  it  by  the  shortest  path  and  in  the 
shortest  time.  But  when  a  ray  is  refracted  by  passing  from  a  uni- 
form medium  to  one  of  different  density,  the  ray  neither  describes 
the  shortest  space  nor  does  it  take  the  shortest  time  about  it.  As 
Fermat  showed,  the  time  would  be  the  shortest  if  light  moved  more 
quickly  in  rarer  media,  but  Newton  proved  that,  as  Descartes  had 
believed,  light  moves  more  quickly  in  denser  media.  Maupertuis's 
discovery  was  that  light  neither  takes  always  the  shortest  path  nor 
always  that  path  which  it  describes  in  the  shortest  time,  but  "that 
for  which  the  quantity  of  action  is  the  least/' 

"I  must  now  explain,"  he  went  one,18  "what  I  mean  by  the  quan- 
tity of  action.  A  certain  action  is  necessary  for  the  carrying  of  a 
body  from  one  point  to  another :  this  action  depends  on  the  velocity 
which  the  body  has  and  the  space  which  it  describes ;  but  it  is  neither 
the  velocity  nor  the  space  taken  separately.  The  quantity  of  action 
varies  directly  as  the  velocity  and  the  length  of  path  described ;  it  is 
proportional  to  the  sum  of  the  spaces,  each  being  multiplied  by  the 
velocity  with  which  the  body  describes  it.  It  is  this  quantity  of 
action  which  is  here  the  true  expense  (depense)  of  nature,  and  which 
she  economizes  as  much  as  possible  in  the  motion  of  light." 

Then  Maupertuis  found,  as  a  consequence  of  his  principle,  that 
the  sine  of  the  angle  of  incidence  is  to  the  sine  of  the  angle  of  re- 
fraction in  the  inverse  ratio  of  the  velocity  of  the  light  in  each  me- 
dium. T9  After  showing  that  the  law  of  reflection  also  follows  from 

17  Maupertuis  afterwards  stated  (see  below,  section  V)  that  the  agreement 
was  between  the  laws  of  the  motion  of  light  and  mechanical  laws.     I  have 
given  below  my  grounds  for  almost  suspecting  that  this  was  not  what  Mau- 
pertuis originally  meant. 

18  Histoire  de  V Academic,  1744,  p.  423;  (Euvres,  vol.  iv,  p.  17.    Notice  that 
here,  in  the  general  definition,  mass  is  not  mentioned.    This  is  another  reason 
for  believing  that,  at  first,  Maupertuis  only  considered  the  motion  of  light- 
corpuscles,  and  not  that  of  ordinary  matter. 

19  Cf.  Mach,  Mechanik,  pp.  397-398 ;  Mechanics,  pp.  367-368.    Using  Mau- 
pertuis's  and  Mach's  figure,  CRD  is  the  horizontal  refracting  plane,  AR  is  the 
incident  and  RB  the  refracted  ray  (A  and  B  being  any  points  chosen  on  these 
respective  rays),  m  the  velocity  of  light  along  AR  and  n  the  velocity  along 
RB.     Then  Maupertuis  says  correctly  that,  according  to  his  principle,  w.AR 
+n.RB  must  be  a  minimum.    That  is  to  say 

d[mV(AC2+CR2)  +  nV(BD2+DR2)]  =o, 

whence,  carrying  out  the  differentiations,  observing  that  AC  and  BD  are  con- 
stant, and  rf(CR)  —  — rf(DR), 

(CR/AR  :  DR/BR)  : :  n  :  m,  or  (sin  CAR/sin  RED)  =  (w/m), 
which  is  correct  on  the  corpuscular  hypothesis;   Mach's  criticism  that  the 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  419 

his  principle  of  the  least  quantity  of  action,  Maupertuis  concluded  :20 
"We  cannot  doubt  that  all  things  are  regulated  by  a  supreme  Being, 
who,  while  he  has  imprinted  on  matter  forces  which  show  his  power, 

has  destined  it  to  execute  effects  which  mark  his  wisdom ; " 

And  :21  "Let  us  calculate  the  motion  of  bodies,  but  let  us  also  consult 
the  designs  of  the  Intelligence  which  makes  them  move." 

It  is  of  interest,  in  connection  with  the  dispute  with  Konig 
which  arose  afterwards,  to  read  the  note  which  Maupertuis  appended 
to  the  reprint  in  his  (Euvres:22 

"When  I  read  the  preceding  memoir  in  the  Paris  Academy  of 
Sciences,  I  only  knew  of  what  Leibniz  had  done  on  this  matter  by 
what  M.  de  Mayran  says  of  it  in  his  memoir  on  the  reflection  of 
bodies  in  the  Paris  Memoir es  for  1723.  Like  him,  I  had  confused 
this  opinion  of  Leibniz's  with  that  of  Fermat.  ..." 

Then  he  gave,2^  after  Euler,2*  the  full  opinion  of  Leibniz.2* 

Now  we  shall  see  below  that  Maupertuis  in  the  Histoire  for 
1752  said  that  he  had  "adopted"  Leibniz's  definition  of  action.  We 
have  no  means  of  knowing  how  far,  if  at  all,  Maupertuis  was  in- 
debted to  the  ideas  of  Leibniz. 

IV. 

There  is  nothing  on  the  subject  of  the  principle  of  the  least 
quantity  of  action  in  the  Histoire  de  I' Academic  de  Berlin  (which 
contains  the  Memoir  es  of  the  various  classes  of  the  Academy)  for 
1745 ;  but,  in  the  Histoire  for  1746,  published  in  1748,  Maupertuis 

reciprocal  values  appear  instead  of  the  actual  ones  is  only  true,  as  P.  Stackel 
observed  in  the  Encykl.  der  math.  Wiss.,  vol.  iv,  part  i,  1908,  p.  491,  on  the 
undulatory  theory,  which  Maupertuis,  as  a  good  Newtonian,  did  not  adopt. 

Further,  Maupertuis's  principle  does  state  that  w.AR-f-w.RB  (which  is 
what  $v.ds  reduces  to  here)  is  to  be  a  minimum.  This  was  contested  by 
Mach  (but  cf.  Mechanik,  p.  406;  Mechanics,  pp.  375-376). 

Du  Bois-Reymond  (op.  cit).,  pp.  48-49)  speaks  of  the  example  of  the 
motion  of  light  which  Maupertuis  chose  in  1744  to  illustrate  his  principle 
being  "not  happily  chosen,"  because  experiments  have  proved  that  the  velocity 
of  light  in  air  is  greater  than  that  in  water — the  opposite  state  of  things  to 
that  which  the  emission  theory  required. 

20  (Euvres,  vol.  iv,  p.  21. 

21  Ibid.,  p.  22. 
"Ibid.,  p.  23. 

23  Ibid.,  pp.  23-28.     In  the  text  of  the  memoir  of  1744,  Maupertuis  (ibid., 
p.   15)   thus  mentioned  Leibniz:  "Leibniz  wished  to  conciliate  the  opinion  of 
Descartes    [that  light  moves  more  quickly  in  the  denser  media]    with  final 
causes ;  but  he  did  this  only  by  suppositions  which  could  not  be  sustained,  and 
which  did  not  square  with  the  other  phenomena  of  nature." 

24  Hist,  de  I'Acad.  de  Berlin,  vol.  vii,  1751,  pp.  205-209. 

25  Acta  Eruditorum,  1682  (not  seen). 


42O  THE  MONIST. 

has26  a  memoir:  "Les  Loix  du  Mouvement  et  du  Repos,  deduites 
d'un  Principe  Metaphysique." 

This  memoir  begins  with  the  prefatory  remark:2?  "I  gave  the 
principle  on  which  the  following  work  is  founded  on  April  15th, 
1744,  in  the  public  assembly  of  the  Royal  Academy  of  Sciences  of 
Paris,  as  the  A  eta  of  this  Academy  testify."  Then  Maupertuis  refers 
to  Euler's  Methodus  inveniendi  of  1744,28  and  the  special  pleasure 
that  the  Appendix  gave  him,  "as,"  he  says,  rather  patronizingly 
and  in  words  which  led  some29  to  suppose  that  Euler  merely  applied 
Maupertuis's  principle,  "it  is  a  beautiful  application  of  my  principle 
to  the  motion  of  the  planets,  of  which  this  principle  is  in  fact  the 
rule." 

The  memoir  is  composed  of  three  parts:  (1)  Examination  of 
the  proofs  of  the  existence  of  God,  which  are  drawn  from  the 
wonders  of  nature  ;3°  (2)  The  thesis  that  these  proofs  must  be  sought 
in  the  general  laws  of  motion,  and  that  the  laws  according  to  which 
motion  is  conserved,  distributed,  and  destroyed  are  founded  on  the 
attributes  of  a  supreme  intelligence  ;^r  and  (3)  Investigation  of  the 
laws  of  motion  and  rest.32  In  the  third  part,  Maupertuis^  states 
the  general  principle  that  "when  some  change  happens  in  nature, 
the  quantity  of  action  necessary  for  this  change  is  the  smallest  pos- 
sible," and  adds:  "The  quantity  of  action  is  the  product  of  the  mass 
of  the  bodies  by  their  velocity  and  by  the  space  which  they  describe. 
When  a  body  is  transported  from  one  place  to  another,  the  action 
is  greater  in  proportion  as  the  mass  is  greater,  as  the  velocity  is 
greater,  and  as  the  path  by  which  it  is  transported  is  longer."  From 
this  principle,  Maupertuis  deduces  the  laws  of  impact  of  hard  (or 
inelastic)  and  elastic  bodies,34  and  of  the  lever.35 

28  Pp.  267-294.  The  mathematical  (third)  part  of  this  memoir  is,  in  part, 
identical  with  "Recherche  des  Loix  du  Mouvement"  in  the  (Euvres,  vol.  iv, 
pp.  31-42;  the  theological  part  is  included  in  the  Essai  de  Cosmologie  to  which 
we  will  soon  refer. 

™  Histoire  de  VAcad.  de  Berlin,  1746,  p.  267.  This  note  was  repeated  in 
Maupertuis's  (Euvres,  vol.  i  (see  below). 

28  See  below,  section  IX. 

29  For  example  La  Beaumelle,  op.  cit.,  p.  85. 
s°Histoire  de  VAcad.  de  Berlin,  1746,  pp.  268-277. 
31  Ibid.,  pp.  277-287. 

™  Ibid.,  pp.  287-294. 

33  Ibid.,  p.  290 ;  CEuvres,  vol.  iv,  p.  36. 

34  Histoire,  pp.  290-293;  (Euvres,  vol.  iv,  pp.  36-42. 

a  tlistoire,  p.  294;  not  in  the  (Euvres.  The  explanation  of  this  omission 
given  by  Maupertuis  ((Euvres,  vol.  i,  p.  xxvii)  is  that  this  problem  is  too  lim- 
ited (as  the  directions  of  the  forces  of  weight  are  all  supposed  to  be  parallel 
to  one  another  and  at  right  angles  to  the  straight  lever)  ;  but  the  "Loi  du 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  42! 

When  treating  of  impact  of  hard  (inelastic)  bodies  of  masses  A 
and  B,  which  move  with  the  velocities  a  and  b  respectively  in  a  straight 
line  and  in  the  same  sense,  Maupertuis  considers  the  spaces  (a  and 
b)  described  in  a  certain  time  (the  unit  of  time),  so  that  m.v.s  be- 
comes m.v2,  as  Mach  notices,  and  so  he  points  out  Maupertuis's 
inconsistency  .s6 

Let  A  move  faster  than  B,  so  that  A  catches  B  up  and  infringes 
on  it,  and  let  the  common  velocity  of  A  and  B  after  the  impact  be  x 
(less  than  a  and  greater  than  b).  "The  alteration  which  has  hap- 
pened in  the  universe  consists  in  that  the  body  A  which  moved  with 
the  velocity  a  and  which  in  a  certain  time  described  a  space  equal  to 
a  only  moves  with  the  velocity  a  and  describes  a  space  equal  to  x, 
while  the  body  B  which  only  moved  with  the  velocity  b  and  described 
a  space  equal  to  b  moves  with  a  velocity  x  and  describes  a  space 
equal  to  x.  This  change  is,  then,  the  same  as  would  have  happened 
if,  while  A  moved  with  the  velocity  a  and  described  a  space  equal  to 
ttj  it  had  been  carried  backwards  through  a  space  equal  to  a-x  on 
an  immaterial  plane  moving  with  the  velocity  a-x,  and  while  B 
moved  with  the  velocity  b  and  described  a  space  equal  to  b,  it  had 
been  carried  forward  through  a  space  equal  to  x  -  b  on  an  immaterial 
plane  moving  with  a  velocity  x  —  b.  Now,  whether  A  and  B  move 
with  their  own  velocities  on  movable  planes  or  they  are  at  rest  there, 
as  the  movement  of  these  planes  charged  with  bodies  is  the  same, 
the  quantities  of  action  produced  in  nature  will  be  A  (a  —  j*)2  and 
B(^r  —  b)2,  and  their  sum  must  be  as  small  as  possible."  This  gives 

2.A. 
whence 


In  this  case,  where  the  bodies  move  in  the  same  direction,  the 
quantity  of  motion  destroyed  and  the  quantity  produced  are  equal, 
and  the  total  quantity  of  motion  remains,  after  the  impact,  the  same 
as  it  was  before.  If  the  bodies  move  towards  one  another  it  is  easy 
to  apply  the  same  reasoning  ;  or  it  is  sufficient  to  consider  b  as  nega- 
tive with  respect  to  a.  Then  the  common  velocity  will  be 


If  A  and  B  are  perfectly  elastic,  and  move  in  the  same  direction 
with  velocities  as  before,  except  that  a  and  ft  are  the  respective 

repos"  of  1740,  given  in  vol.  iv  of  the  CEuvres,  is  a  general  principle  of  statics 
and  "agrees  so  perfectly  with  the  principle  of  the  least  quantity  of  action  that 
we  may  say  that  it  is  only  the  same  thing." 

MMechanik,  pp.  395-396,  398;  Mechanics,  pp.  365-366,  368. 


422  THE  MONIST. 

velocities  after  impact,  "the  sum  or  the  difference  of  these  velocities 
after  the  impact  being  the  same  as  it  was  before,"  then,  by  analogous 
considerations  on  the  change  which  has  happened  in  nature,  Mau- 
pertuis  arrives  at  the  conclusion  that  the  quantity  of  action  is  here 


and  this,  when  minimized,  since 

(3-a  =  a-b  and  thus  dp  =  da, 
gives 

a=  (Aa-Ba-2B&)/(A  +  B),        13=  (2Aa+Ab-Bb)/(A  +  E). 

Here  the  sum  of  the  vires  vivae  is  conserved  on  impact,  but  this 
is  not  the  case  with  hard  (inelastic)  bodies. 

To  find  the  law  of  the  lever  Maupertuis  considers  masses  A 
and  B  attached  to  the  ends  of  an  immaterial  lever  of  length  c,  and 
seeks  the  point,  at  a  distance  z  from  A,  around  which  they  are  in 
equilibrium.  For  this  purpose  he  seeks  the  point  around  which,  if 
the  lever  receives  some  small  movement,  the  quantity  of  action  is  the 
smallest  possible.  Then  A  and  B,  on  this  movement  being  im- 
parted to  them,  describe  small  arcs  similar  to  one  another  and  pro- 
portional to  the  distances  of  these  bodies  from  the  point  sought. 
These  arcs  will  be  the  spaces  described  by  the  bodies  and  at  the 
same  time  will  represent  their  velocities.  Thus  the  quantity  of  action 
will  be  proportional  to 


and  this,  when  minimized,  gives 


v. 

In  the  "Avertissement"  to  the  fourth  volume  of  his  (Euvres, 
Maupertuis  says  of  the  memoir  of  1744:  "I  show  the  agreement  of 
the  laws  which  light  follows  in  its  reflection  and  its  refraction  with 
those  which  all  other  bodies  follow  in  their  motion."  In  point  of 
fact,  this  is  not  quite  the  case:  he  shows  how  both  the  law  of  re- 
flection and  that  of  refraction  could,  on  the  corpuscular  hypothesis, 
be  deduced  from  one  principle  ;  but,  in  the  whole  memoir,  other  mo- 
tions than  that  of  light  were  only  referred  to  shortly.  The  law  that, 
in  a  uniform  medium,  light  moves  in  a  straight  line  is  common,  he 
says,37  to  all  bodies  :  they  move  in  a  straight  line  unless  some  external 
force  deflects  them;  and  the  law  of  reflection  is  the  same  as  that 
87  Paris  Histoire,  1744,  p.  418;  CEuvres,  vol.  iv,  p.  7. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  423 

followed  by  an  elastic  ball  impinging  on  an  unbreakable  surface. 
But  no  like  explanation  of  the  law  of  refraction  had  been  given. 

Later  on,  Maupertuis38  adds  a  note  to  his  definition  of  the 
quantity  of  action  as  2s.v:  "As  here  there  is  only  one  body,  we  ab- 
stract from  its  mass." 

VI. 

Maupertuis's  Essai  de  Cosmologie  was  published  in  175 1,39  and 
consists  of  three  parts:  (1)  Examination  of  the  proofs  of  the  exis- 
tence of  God,  which  are  drawn  from  the  wonders  of  nature;  (2) 
Deduction  of  the  laws  of  motion  from  the  attributes  of  the  supreme 
intelligence;  and  (3)  Spectacle  of  the  universe.  No  part  of  the 
work  is  stated  mathematically,  and  the  third  part  is  a  rhetorical 
sketch  of  the  solar  system,  in  which  the  principle  of  the  least  quan- 
tity of  action  is  not  mentioned.40  The  two  first  parts  are  practically 
the  two  first  parts  of  the  memoir  of  1746. 

38  CEuvres,  vol.  iv,  p.  17.    This  note  is  not  in  the  original  memoir  of  1744 
(the  paragraph  in  the  text  to  which  the  note  refers  is  on  p.  423  of  this  mem- 
oir), but  was  first  added,  as  a  marginal  note,  in  the  Essai  de  Cosmologie  of 
1751.     These  facts  suggest  that  the  mechanical  applications  of  Maupertuis's 
principle  were,  at  least,  not  clear  to  Maupertuis  in  1744.     For  my  own  part, 
I   cannot   help   almost  having  the   impression   from   a   study  of  the   original 
memoir  of  1744  and  its  reproduction,  with  comments,  in  the  CEuvres  of  1756, 
that  the  laws  of  nature  referred  to  in  1744  are  the  laws  of  catoptrics  and 
dioptrics,    whereas    afterwards    Maupertuis,   because   of   the    discovery   com- 
municated in  his   memoir  of   1746,  tried  to   persuade  possibly  himself  and 
certainly  his  readers  that  the  laws  were  more  general  laws  of  nature.     Cf. 
Note  18,  Section  III,  above. 

Formey,  in  the  Eloge  quoted  at  the  beginning  of  this  paper,  says  (p.  496)  : 
"II  y  [in  the  memoir  of  1744]  etoit  principalement  question  des  loix  qui  suit 
la  lumiere,  surtout  lorsqu'elle  passe  d'un  milieu  diaphane  dans  un  autre." 

39  Essay  de  Cosmologie.     Par  M.  de  Maupertuis,  Leyden,  1751.     At  the 
end  (pp.  81-104)   is  a  reprint  of  the  1744  paper  with  the  mathematics   (the 
note  referred  to  in  section  V,  last  note,  is  put  in  the  margin  of  pp.  97-98)  ; 
and  on  pp.  63-80  is  a  "Recherche  mathematique  des  Loix  du  Mouvement  et 
du  Repos,"  from,  says  Maupertuis,  the  Berlin  Memoires  for  1747  (a  misprint 
for  1746).    The  Essai  was  partly  reprinted  in  the  first  volume  of  the  CEuvres 
de  Mr.  de  Maupertuis  (Nouvelle  edition,  corrigee  et  augmentee,  Lyons,  1756,  pp. 
3-78,  and  the  mathematical  part,  which  was  omitted  in  the  previous  editions 
of  Maupertuis's  CEuvres,  is  included  in  vol.  iv,  pp.  18-19,  36-42.     On  pp.  iii- 
xxviii,  is  an  "avant-propos"  giving,  among  other  things,  an  account  of  the 
Koenig  incident  of  1751  and  its  consequences.     On  pp.  xiv-xv  is  the  same 
notice  about  his  own  and  Euler's  works  of  1744  that  is  at  the  head  of  Mau- 
pertuis's paper  in  the  Berlin  Memoires  for  1746.    On  d'Arcy's  objections  (see 
section  XV)    Maupertuis    (CEuvres,  vol.   i,  p.   xxvi)    said  that  'As  the  only 
objection  which  appears  to  have  some  foundation  rests  on  the  fact  that,  in  the 
impact  of  elastic  bodies,  he  has  confused  the  change  which  happens  to  the 
velocities  (which  is  real)  with  the  change  of  the  quantity  of  action  (which  is 
zero),  I  will  make  no  other  reply  than  the  few  words  I  have  said  about  it  in 
the  Memoires  of  our  [Berlin]  Academy  for  the  year  1752"  (see  section  XVI). 

*° However,  in  the  second  part  (CEuvres,  vol.  i,  p.  45),  we  read:  "What 
a  satisfaction  for  the  human  mind  to  find  in  the  laws  which  are  the  principle 


424  THE  MONIST. 

Maupertuis  had  a  low  opinion  of  the  proofs  of  the  existence  of 
God  from  the  construction  of  animals.  Thus,  somebody^  found 
evidence  for  this  existence  in  the  folds  of  the  skin  of  a  rhinoceros — 
the  animal  could  not  move  without  these  folds.  Maupertuis^2  rather 
appositely  asked :  "What  would  be  said  of  a  man  who  should  deny 
a  Providence  because  the  shell  of  a  tortoise  has  neither  folds  nor 
joints?"  And -.43  "It  is  not  in  the  little  details,  in  those  parts  of  the 
universe  of  whose  relations  are  known  too  little,  that  we  must  look 
for  the  supreme  Being,  but  in  phenomena  whose  universality  suffers 
no  exception  and  whose  simplicity  lays  them  quite  open  to  our  sight." 

VII. 

The  reason  why  Maupertuis  laid  stress  on  the  deduction  from 
the  principle  of  the  least  quantity  of  action  of  the  laws  of  the  impact 
of  inelastic  masses  was  that  the  law  of  the  conservation  of  vis  viva 
fails  in  this  case.44  Leibniz^s  recognized  Descartes's  error  in  think- 
ing that,  in  nature,  the  sum  of  the  products  of  the  masses  into  their 
respective  velocities  is  constant,  and  substituted  in  it  the  squares  of 
the  velocities  for  the  velocities,  so  that  the  sum  is  what  is  called  the 
vis  viva  of  the  system  considered.  But,  in  impact,  the  vis  viva  is 
only  conserved  if  the  bodies  are  elastic ;  and,  according  to  Mauper- 
tuis :«6  "When  we  make  this  objection  to  the  Leibnizians,  they  pre- 
fer to  say  that  there  are  no  hard  (durs,  inelastic)  bodies  in  nature 
than  to  abandon  their  principle.  This  were  to  be  reduced  to  the 
strangest  paradox  to  which  love  of  a  system  could  reduce  one:  for 
what  can  the  primitive  elementary  bodies  be  but  hard  bodies?" 

In  vain,  then,  said  Maupertuis,47  did  Descartes  and  Leibniz,  in 

of  motion  of  all  the  bodies  of  the  universe  the  proof  of  the  existence  of  the 
governor  of  it !" 

"•Phil.  Trans.,  No.  470.  [The  paper  referred  to  is  entitled:  "A  Letter 
from  Dr.  Parsons  to  Martin  Folkes,  Esq.,  President  of  the  Roy.  Soc.,  con- 
taining the  Natural  History  of  the  Rhinoceros,"  and  is  printed  in  the  Phil. 
Trans,  for  1743,  pp.  523-541]. 

42  CEuvres,  vol.  i,  p.  12. 

"Ibid.,  p.  21. 

44  CEuvres,  vol.  i,  pp.  xvi-xvii,  44. 

45  On  Leibniz's  mechanics   (the  conservation  of  vis  viva,  and  so  on),  cf. 
Bertrand  Russell,  A  Critical  Exposition  of  the  Philosophy  of  Leibniz,  with  an 
Appendix  of  leading  Passages,  Cambridge,  1900,  pp.  77-99,  226-238;  esp.  pp. 
89-90.    The  concept  of  action  with  Leibniz  was  not  mentioned  by  Russell ;  on 
it  cf.  du  Bois-Reymond,  op.  cit.,  pp.  48,  51,  89-90;  and  Helmholtz,  "Zur  Ge- 
schichte   des    Princips    der   kleinsten    Action,"   Sitzungsberichte   der   Berliner 
Akad.,  1887,  pp.  225-236,  or  Wiss.  Abh.,  vol.  iii,  pp.  249-263.    Cf.  also  L.  Cou- 
turat,  La  logique  de  Leibniz,  1901,  pp.  229-233,  577-581. 

48  Op.  cit.,  p.  xvii. 
47  Ibid.,  p.  xviii. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  425 

different  ways,  imagine  a  world  which  could  dispense  with  the  hand 
of  a  Creator :  no  quantity  which  can  be  regarded  as  a  cause  in  the 
distribution  of  motion  subsists  unaltered.  But  "Action"  is,  so  to 
speak,  created  at  each  instant,  and  always  created  with  the  greatest 
economy  possible ;  and  by  this  the  universe  announces  its  dependence 
on  a  wise  and  powerful  author. 

Maupertuis*8  said  that,  because  he  held  that  the  conservation  of 
vis  viva  is  not  the  universal  principle  of  movement,  the  whole  sect 
of  Leibnizians  in  Germany  descended  on  him  (je  vis  fondre  sur  moi 
toute  la  secte  que  M.  de  Leybnitz  a  laissee  en  Allemagne),  and  then 
mentioned49  Konig's  having  attributed  some  of  Maupertuis's  and 
Euler's  discoveries  to  Leibniz.  Then  followss°  an  account  of  the 
incident. 

As  a  justification  of  the  word  "action,"  MaupertuisS1  remarked 
that  he  had  found  this  word  quite  established  by  Leibniz  and  Wolff, 
and  did  not  wish  to  change  the  terms. 

VIII. 

When  speaking  of  Diderot's  Thoughts  on  the  Interpretation  of 
Nature  of  1754,  John  Morley,52  now  Lord  Morley,  said : 

"Maupertuis  had  in  1751,  under  the  assumed  name  of  Baumann, 
an  imaginary  doctor  of  Erlangen,  published  a  dissertation  on  the 
Universal  System  of  Nature,  in  which  he  seems  to  have  maintained 
that  the  mechanism  of  the  universe  is  one  and  the  same  throughout, 
modifying  itself,  or  being  modified  by  some  vital  element  within,  in 
an  infinity  of  diverse  ways.53  Leibnitz's  famous  idea,  of  making 
nature  invariably  work  with  the  minimum  of  action,  was  seized  by 
Maupertuis,  expressed  as  the  Law  of  Thrift,  and  made  the  starting 
point  of  speculations  that  led  directly  to  Holbach  and  the  System 
of  Nature  s*  The  Loi  d'Epargnc  evidently  tended  to  make  unity 

48  Ibid.,  p.  xix. 

"Ibid.,  p.  xx. 

50  Ibid.,  pp.  xx-xxvi,  cf.  section  XI  below. 

01  Ibid.,  pp.  xxvi-xxvii,  cf.  Maupertuis's  paper  of  1752,  described  below  in 
section  XVI. 

52  Diderot  and  the  Encyclopedists,  vol.  ii,  London,  edition  of  1905,  pp.  262- 
263. 

63  "As  to  the  precise  drift  of  Maupertuis's  theme,  see  Lange,  Gesch.  d. 
Materialismus,  i,  413,  n.  37.  Also  Rosenkranz,  Diderot's  Leben,  1866,  vol.i, 
P.  I34-" 

54  "In  1765  Grimm  describes  the  principle  of  Leibnitz  and  Maupertuis  as 
'gaining  on  us  on  every  side'. ..  .Corr.  Lit.,  iv,  186."  [Under  the  date  of  Feb. 
T5>  J765,  Grimm  (Correspondance  litteraire  philosophique  et  critique  de  Grimm 
et  de  Diderot  depuis  1753  jusqu'en  1790,  new  ed.,  vol.  iv,  p.  186)  speaks  thus 


426  THE  MONIST. 

of  all  the  forces  of  the  universe  the  keynote  or  the  goal  of  philo- 
sophical inquiry.  At  this  time  of  his  life,  Diderot  resisted  Mau- 
pertuis's  theory  of  the  unity  of  vital  force  in  the  universe,  or  per- 
haps we  should  rather  say  that  he  saw  how  open  it  was  to  criticism. 
His  resistance  has  none  of  his  usual  air  of  vehement  conviction. 
However  that  may  be,  the  theory  excited  his  interest,  and  fitted  in 
with  the  train  of  meditation  which  his  thoughts  about  the  Encyclo- 
paedia had  already  set  in  motion,  and  of  which  the  Pensees  Philo- 
sophiques  of  1746  were  the  cruder  prelude." 

Again  :ss 

"Diderot  was  in  no  sense  the  originator  of  the  French  material- 
ism of  the  eighteenth  century.  He  was  preceded  by  Maupertuis, 
by  Robinet,  and  by  La  Mettrie ;  and  we  have  already  seen  that  when 
he  composed  the  Thoughts  on  the  Interpretation  of  Nature  (1754) 
he  did  not  fully  accept  Maupertuis's  materialistic  thesis.  Lange  has 
shown  that  at  a  very  early  period  in  the  movement  the  most  consis- 
tent materialism  was  ready  and  developed,  while  such  leaders  of  the 
movement  as  Voltaire  and  Diderot  still  leaned  either  on  deism  and 
scepticism. "s6 

Lange'sS7  work  was  first  published  in  one  volume:  Geschichte 
des  Materialismus  und  Kritik  seiner  Bedeutung  in  der  Gegenwart 
at  Iserlohn  in  1866.  In  the  whole  book,  Maupertuis  is  only  men- 
tioned once.  On  page  224s8  it  is  said  that  people  debated  whether 
the  Marquis  d'Argens  (Jean  Baptiste  de  Boyer)  or  Maupertuis  or 
some  personal  enemy  of  Albrecht  von  Haller,  really  wrote  the 
Homme  machine  which  De  la  Mettrie  ironically  dedicated  to  Von 
Haller.59 

The  fourth  part60  is  devoted  to  the  materialism  of  the  eighteenth 
century,  and  consists  of  three  divisions:  De  la  Mettrie's  Homme 
machine  of  1747  ;61  Holbach's  Systeme  de  la  Nature,  ou  des  lois  du 
monde  physique  et  du  monde  moral  of  1770,  published,  according 
to  the  title-page,  in  London,  but  really  at  Amsterdam,  under  the 

of  the  Leibniz-Maupertuis  principle  of  thrift,  immediately  after  speaking  of 
the  second  volume  of  Robinet's  De  la  nature,  published  in  four  volumes 
1761-8. 

On  Holbach's  System  of  Nature  (1770),  see  Morley,  op.  cit.,  pp.  155-203. 

55  Morley,  op.  cit.,  pp.  272-273. 

58  Gesch.  d.  Materialismus,  \,  309,  310,  etc. 

57  Friedrich  Albert  Lange. 

58  Cf.  the  references  below  the  second  edition  of  Lange's  work. 

59  Lange,  op.  cit.,  p.  72. 

60  Ibid.,  pp.  163-229. 

61  Ibid.,  pp.  163-186. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  427 

name  of  Mirabaud  who  had  been  dead  for  ten  years  ;62  and  the  Ger- 
man reaction  against  materialism.^ 

On  the  other  hand,  Maupertuis  is  often  spoken  of  in  the  second 
edition  of  Lange's  work,  published  at  Iserlohn  in  1873  and  1875  in 
two  volumes  under  the  same  title,64  and  it  is  to  this  edition  that 
Morley's  citations  refer.  We  will  continue  this  reference  to  Lange's 
book  after  having  given  some  information  about  Maupertuis's  work 
of  1751,  which  Morley  mentions. 

In  1751  Maupertuis  published  at  Erlangen,  under  the  pseudo- 
nym of  "Baumann,"  a  Latin  dissertation  under  the  title:  Dissertatio 
inaugurate  metaphysica,  de  universali  naturae  systemata,6*  in  which 

62  Ibid.,  pp.  186-214. 

63  Ibid.,  pp.  214-229. 

64  There  is  an  English  translation  of  this  edition  in  three  volumes,  by  E. 
C.  Thomas,  published  at  London  in  1877,  1880  and  1881  (History  of  Material- 
ism and  Criticism  of  its  Present  Importance').    The  passages  in  this  transla- 
tion parallel  to  those  of  Morley's  citations  are  given  here. 

65  Another  edition,  with  a  French  translation  and  with  neither  the  place 
nor  year  of  publication  has  been  given;  a  third,  only  in  French  and  entitled: 
Essai  sur  la  formation  des  corps  organisees  was  published  by  1'Abbe  Trublet, 
with  a  notice  and  conjectures  about  the  author,  at  Berlin  (really  at  Paris)  in 
1754;  and  the  French  version  (Systeme  de  la  Nature:  Essai  sur  la  formation 
des  corps  organisees}  was  published,  with  a  preface,  in  Maupertuis's  (Euvres, 
1756,  vol.  ii,  pp.  135-168  (between  pp.  160  and  161  are  pages  numbered  145* 
to  *i6o).     Diderot's  Pensees  sur  I' interpretation  de  la  nature  was  published 
anonymously  at  Paris  in  1754  with  "London"  as  the  place  of  printing   (Cf. 
Karl  Rosenkranz,  Diderot's  Leben  und  Werke,  2  vols.,  Leipsic,  1866,  vol.  i, 
pp.  134-146;  (Euvres  completes  de  Diderot,  ed.  by  J.  Assezat,  vol.  ii,  Paris, 
1875,  pp.  1-63 ;  cf.  Assezat's  "Notice  preliminaire,"  p.  3.     Maupertuis's  "Re- 
ponse  aux  objections  de  M.  Diderot,"  was  printed  in  his  (Euvres,  1756,  vol.  ii, 
pp.  169-184  (between  pp.  176  and  177  are  pages  numbered  161*  to  *I76).    Cf. 
on  all  this,  La  Beaumelle,  op.  cit.,  pp.  178-181,  200-201. 

On  Maupertuis's  theories  of  generation,  see  La  Beaumelle,  op.  cit.,  pp. 
86-87,  98-103;  du  Bois-Reymond,  op.  cit.,  pp.  38-39,  44-45.  The  Venus  phy- 
sique of  1745  (anonymous)  was  republished  in  Maupertuis's  (Euvres,  1756, 
vol.  ii,  pp.  1-133.  The  statement  that  Maupertuis  endeavored  to  explain  the 
formation  of  the  foetus  by  gravitation  is  one  of  Voltaire's  libels  on  Mauper- 
tuis. The  truth  seems  to  be  that  Maupertuis,  in  his  Venus  and  Systeme  de  la 
Nature,  as  well  as  in  one  of  his  Letters  ("Lettre  xiv,  Sur  la  generation  des 
animaux,"  (Euvres,  1756,  vol.  ii,  pp.  267-282),  tried  to  explain  this  formation 
by  the  different  attractions  or  (in  the  Systeme}  psychical  tendencies  of  the 
"different  parts.  The  Lettres  de  M.  de  Maupertuis  (sur  differ  ents  sujets}  were 
published  in  1753  and  again  in  the  (Euvres,  1756,  vol.  ii,  pp.  185-340,  after 
having  been  grossly  caricatured  by  Voltaire  in  his  Histoire  du  docteur  Akakia 
et  du  natif  de  Saint  Malo  ((Euvres  completes  de  Voltaire,  vol.  xxiv,  Paris, 
1892,  pp.  358-376).  By  the  way,  Letters  X  and  XI  ("Sur  les  loix  du  mouve- 
ment"  and  "Sur  ce  qui  s'est  passe  a  1'occasion  du  principe  de  la  moindre  quan- 
tite  de  1'action";  (Euvres,  1756,  vol.  ii,  pp.  238-242  and  243-251  respectively) 
refer  to  the  principle  of  least  action;  and  Letter  XII  (ibid.,  pp.  252-257;  "Sur 
1 'attraction")  contains  a  short  expose  of  Maupertuis's  work  in  introducing 
Newtonianism  into  France. 

Maupertuis  does  not  seem,  by  his  published  writings,  to  have  been  nearly 
so  ridiculous  a  person  as  Voltaire,  for  personal  reasons,  tried  to  make  him 
appear  to  be.  And  Voltaire's  sarcasms  have  had  great  influence  on  the  ideas 


428  THE  MONIST. 

a  hypothesis  that  the  parts  of  matter  have  something  similar  to 
what  we  call  desire,  aversion,  and  memory  was  advanced  to  explain 
certain  physiological  facts.  Maupertuis  chose  this  pseudonymous 
fashion  of  giving  his  thoughts  to  the  public,  partly  because  the 
work  of  an  unknown  author  would  be  less  the  butt  of  objections, 
and  partly  in  order  that  he  should  not  be  obliged  to  reply  to  them. 
But  he  felt  it  necessary  to  reply  to  Diderot's  Thoughts  because  his 
doctrines  were  accused  of  having  results  contrary  to  religion.  Then 
he  acknowledged  the  work:  he  had  soon  been  recognized  as  its 
author.  What  concerns  us  here  is  that  the  law  of  least  action  is 
not  mentioned  in  this  work  of  Maupertuis's.  Further,  the  Essai 
de  Cosmologie  of  1751  was  not  published  anonymously  or  pseudo- 
nymously.  Thus  there  seem  to  be  no  grounds  for  Morley's  strange 
error. 

Lange  shows  that  the  Newtonian  theory  is  a  combination  of 
materialism  in  natural  science  with  a  religious  faith  in  the  spiritual 
constructor  of  the  material  world-machine.  "The  magnificent  phe- 
nomena of  the  seventeenth  century  were  renewed  in  increased  splen- 
dor, and  to  the  age  of  a  Pascal  and  Fermat  succeeded  with  Mau- 
pertuis and  D'Alembert  the  long  series  of  French  mathematicians 
of  the  eighteenth  century,  until  Laplace  drew  the  last  consequences 
of  the  Newtonian  cosmology  in  discarding  even  the  hypothesis  of  a 
creator/'66 

Maupertuis  is  classed  with  Robinet  and  La  Mettrie  as  a  mate- 
rialist^ on  the  grounds  of  his  Latin  dissertation  of  1751.  The 
English  translation  of  the  note  (37)  referred  to  by  Morley  is:68 
"Comp.  Rosenkranz,  Diderot,  i,  134  ff.  The  pseudonymous  disser- 
tation of  Dr.  Baumann  (Maupertuis)  I  have  not  seen,  and  it  may 
be  open  to  some  doubt,  according  to  Diderot  and  Rosenkranz, 
whether  it  does  really  contain  the  materialism  of  Robinet — that  is, 
the  unconditional  dependence  of  the  spiritual  upon  the  purely  me- 
chanical series  of  external  events — or  whether  it  inculcates  Hylo- 

of  Maupertuis  formed  by  succeeding  generations.  Thus  Mach  (Mechanik,  pp. 
484-485,  Mechanics,  po.  454-455)  gives,  I  think,  Voltaire's  version  of  some  of 
the  things  dealt  with  by  Maupertuis  in  a  Letter  published  earlier  than  those 
just  mentioned.  Maupertuis's  Lettre  sur  les  pr ogres  des  sciences  was  pub- 
lished at  Berlin  in  1752  and  again  in  his  CELuvres,  1756,  vol.  ii,  pp.  341-399- 
Here  is  the  project  of  founding  a  town  where  only  Latin  should  be  spoken, 
in  order  to  preserve  this  most  universal  of  languages  (pp.  367-368),  and  a 
plea  (pp.  394-398)  for  "metaphysical" — or,  as  we  would  say  now,  psycho- 
logical— experiments. 

66  Lange,  Geschichte,  2d  ed.,  vol.  i,  p.  304;  History,  vol.  ii,  p.  16. 

67  Lange,  Geschichte,  vol.  i,  p.  310;  History,  vol.  ii,  p.  25. 

68  Lange,  Geschichte,  vol.  i,  pp.  315,  412-413;  History,  vol.  ii,  p.  31. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  429 

zoism — that  is,  modifications  of  the  natural  mechanism  by  the  spirit- 
ual content  of  nature  according  to  other  than  purely  mechanical 
laws." 

Again  :69  "Bnffon  began  the  publication  of  his  great  work  on 
natural  history  in  the  year  1749,  with  the  first  three  volumes ;  but 
it  was  only  in  the  fourth  volume  that  he  unfolded  the  idea  of  the 
unity  of  principle  in  the  multiplicity  of  organisms,  an  idea  which 
occurs  again  in  Maupertuis  in  an  anonymous  work  in  1751,  in  Dide- 
rot in  the  Pcnsccs  sur  r Interpretations  de  la  Nature,  1754,  while  we 
find  it  developed  with  great  clearness  and  distinctness  by  La  Mettrie 
as  early  as  the  L'Homme  Plant e  in  1748." 

This,  together  with  the  passage  referred  to  above,  when  we  were 
speaking  of  the  first  edition,  about  Maupertuis  being  considered  by 
some  to  be  the  author  of  L'Homme  Machine,70  completes  the  list  of 
Lange's  references  to  Maupertuis  in  the  second  edition  of  his  book. 

We  must  add  that  Maupertuis,  in  his  writings  and  in  his  life, 
showed  the  greatest  respect  for  religion.  He  was  by  no  means  a 
materialist  and  atheist/1  and  the  only  reason,  said  he,  that  he  had 
for  replying  to  Diderot's  Thoughts  on  his  dissertation  of  1751  was 
that  Diderot  stated  that  the  dissertation,  in  spite  of  its  carefully  re- 
ligious tone,  led  to  conclusions  which  were  subversive  of  religion. 

IX. 

This  seems  the  best  place  to  give  some  account  of  the  work  of 
a  man  who  will  now  take  a  prominent  place  in  the  development  of 
Maupertuis's  ideas ;  I  mean  Leonhard  Euler.?2 

The  modern  period  of  the  discussion  of  maximal  and  minimal 
problems  begins  with  Johann  Bernoulli's  proposal  of  the  problem  of 
the  brachistochrone  in  1696  and  the  consequent  rise  into  importance 
of  the  "isoperimetrical"  problems. 73  The  period  1696  to  1762  of 

69Lange,  Geschichte,  vol.  i,  p.  328;  History,  vol.  ii,  p.  52. 

70  Lange,  Geschichte,  vol.  i,  p.  398 ;  History,  vol.  ii,  p.  137. 

71  Du  Bois-Reymond,  op.  cit.,  pp.  43-44,  49-50. 

72  On  the  older  period  of  the  history  of  such  problems,  see  Mach,  Mechanik, 
PP-  453-457;  Mechanics,  pp.  421-425.    This  period  is — like  all  early  periods  in 
the  history  of  branches  of  science — characterized  by  the  fact  that  the  maximal 
and  minimal  problems  are  all  isolated.    This  period  extends  as  far  as  Newton 
who  in  1687  solved  "the  first  problem  of  the  calculus  of  variations,"  the  deter- 
mination of  the  figure  of  the  solid  of  least  resistance  (cf.  M.  Cantor,  op.  cit., 
p.  291). 

73  Mach,  Mechanik,  pp.  457-467 ;  Mechanics,  pp.  425-436.     A  German  an- 
notated translation  of  some  works  of  Johann  Bernoulli,  Jakob  Bernoulli,  and 
Leonhard  Euler,  from  1696  to  1744,  is  given  by  P.  Stackel  in  No.  46  of  Ost- 
walds  Klassiker.     Cf.  also  M.  Cantor,  op.  cit.,  pp.  237-241,  384,  446-458,  533, 
846-848. 


430  THE  MONIST. 

the  history  of  such  problems  is  distinguished  by  the  names  of  Johann 
Bernoulli,  Jakob  Bernoulli,  and  Leonhard  Euler,  and  extends  until 
Lagrange,  in  1762,  brought  all  these  interrelated  methods  under  the 
general  and  abstract  analytical  form  of  the  calculus  of  variations. 
It  is  to  this  period  that  the  works  of  Maupertuis,  Euler,  and  their 
contemporaries,  with  which  we  are  concerned  here,  belong.  The 
leading  work  published  in  this  period  was  the  famous  Methodus  in- 
veniendi  tineas  curvas  maximi  minimive  proprietate  gandentes :  sive 
solutio  problematis  isoperimetrici  latissimo  sensu  accepti  which  was 
published  at  Lausanne  and  Geneva  in  1744.74 

Mathematicians  found  that  various  problems  of  mechanics  might 
be  put  into  isoperimetrical  form.  Whether  their  tendency  to  do 
this,  which  was  very  common  at  that  time,  was  due  to  esthetic, 
theological,  or  technical  reasons,  it  is  hard  to  say.  Daniel  Bernoulli 
— a  son  of  Johann  Bernoulli — remarked  that  certain  statical  problems 
can  be  treated  with  greater  facility  by  isoperimetrical  methods  than 
by  the  usual  mechanical  principles ;  the  feeling,  too,  that  the  dis- 
covery that  a  problem  about  natural  objects  could  be  put  in  a  max- 
imal or  minimal  form  had  a  connection  with  the  way  the  Deity 
managed  things  here  below  in  making  nature  act  by  the  shortest 
or  easiest  or  readiest  paths,  and  so  with  what  were  then  called  "meta- 
physical"75 questions,  undoubtedly  had  an  influence  on  others  besides 
Maupertuis — on  Euler  for  example.  But  we  shall  see  how  piety  and 
humility  led  Euler,  though  accurate,  judged  by  the  mathematical 
standards  of  those  days,  very  cautious,  and  perhaps  a  little  unimag- 
inative/6 to  accept  and  admire  the  bold  and  not  always  accurate 
mechanical  generalizations  which  Maupertuis  professed  to  deduce 
from  "metaphysics."  But  probably  the  esthetic  satisfaction  which 

74  An  annotated  German  translation  of  a  great  part  of  this  book  was  given 
in  No.  46  of  Ostwalds  Klassiker.     However,  the  two   appendices    (on   the 
elastic  curves,  and  on  the  motion  of  a  particle  round  a  center  of  force  in  a  non- 
resisting  medium)  with  which  we  shall  be  especially  concerned  here  were  not 
translated  with  the  main  body  of  the  work.    But  the  first  appendix  was  trans- 
lated, in  another  connection,  in  No.  175  of  the  Klassiker  (see  below,  section 
X).    An  account  of  Euler's  book  of  1744  is  given  in  M.  Cantor's  Geschichte, 
vol.  iii,  2d  ed.,  Leipsic,  1901,  pp.  857-867. 

75  In   the    eighteenth    century,    "metaphysics"    stood    for — at   least    among 
mathematicians — a  branch   of  learning  which  included  theology,  psychology, 
and  logic.    Consider  the  "metaphysical  experiments"  advocated  by  Maupertuis, 
and  the  "metaphysics  of  the  infinitesimal  calculus"  (L.  N.  M.  Carnot,  Lagrange, 
and  others),  which  meant  what  we  mean  when  we  say:  "the  logical  principles 
of  the  calculus." 

76  D'Alembert,  in  a  letter  of  March  3,  1766,  to  Voltaire  (quoted  by  Delam- 
bre  in  his  "Notice"  in  CEuvres  de  Lagrange,  vol.  i,  p.  xxi),  says  of  Euler: 
"c'est  un  homme  peu  amtisant,  mais  un  tres  grand  geometre." 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  43! 

arises  from  stating  a  problem  in  a  maximal  or  minimal  form  in- 
fluenced mathematicians  the  most. 

However  this  may  be,  to  this  form  come  many  problems  of 
statics,  such  as  the  catenary  of  Johann  and  Jakob  Bernoulli,77  and 
Jakob  Bernoulli's  problem  of  the  elastic  curve.78  From  Daniel  Ber- 
noulli's letter  to  Euler  and  from  Euler's  first  appendix  to  his  book  of 
1744,  we  see  with  what  interest  Daniel  Bernoulli  and  Euler  reduced 
this  problem  in  the  theory  of  elasticity  to  isoperimetrical  methods. 

These  problems  were  all  statical  ones ;  and  it  was  Daniel  Ber- 
noulli who  suggested  to  Euler  the  putting  of  a  certain  dynamical 
problem  into  isoperimetrical  form.  It  must  be  remembered  that 
Euler,  by  his  papers  published  by  the  St.  Petersburg  Academy  in 
1732  and  1736/9  had  placed  himself  at  the  head  of  the  mathematical 
world,  in  the  treatment  of  isoperimetrical  problems.  We  must  now 
say  some  words  about  Daniel  Bernoulli  and  Euler  and  their  rela- 
tions to  one  another. 

Daniel  Bernoulli80  (1700-1782)  was  a  son  of  the  famous  Jo- 
hann Bernoulli  (1667-1748)  and  was  attached  to  the  St.  Petersburg 
Academy  from  1725  to  1733.  From  1733  to  1782  he  was  Professor 
of  Anatomy  and  Botany,  and  later  Experimental  Physics  and  Specu- 
lative Philosophy  too,  at  Basel.  His  mathematical  works81  are  on 
differential  equations,  the  theory  of  numbers,  the  theory  of  prob- 
ability, series,  and  mechanics82 — principally  the  theorem  of  vis  viva** 
the  problem  of  vibrating  cords,8*  and  hydrodynamics.8*  Leonhard 
Euler86  (1707-1783),  whose  name  as  a  mathematician  is  too  well 
known  for  it  to  be  necessary  for  us  to  refer  further  to  his  many 
works,  came  to  St.  Petersburg  in  1727,  owing  to  the  exertions  on 
his  behalf  of  Daniel  Bernoulli  and  Hermann,  but  left  St.  Peters- 

77  Cf .  Mach,  Mechanik,  pp.  75-77 ;  Mechanics,  pp.  74-76 ;  Ostwalds  Klas- 
siker,  No.  46,  p.  19;  M.  Cantor,  op.  cit.,  pp.  219-220,  228,  235,  289,  384,  455,853. 

78  Cf.   M.   Cantor,  op.  cit.,  pp.  220-221,  and  Johann  Bernoulli's  letter  of 
March  7,  1739,  to  Euler  in  Fuss's  Correspondence  referred  to  below,  vol.  ii, 
pp.  23-25. 

79  Cf.  M.  Cantor,  op.  cit.,  pp.  846-856. 

80  M.  Cantor,  op.  cit.,  pp.  89-90,  550;  Encycl.  Brit.,  9th  ed.,  vol.  iii,  1875, 
pp.  606-607. 

81  Ibid.,  pp.  477-48i,  610,  630-632,  634-635,  640,  642-644,  688,  693,  707,  721, 
851,  900,  904-906. 

82  Cf.  also  Mach,  Mechanik,  pp.  43-49,  326 ;  Mechanics,  pp.  40-47,  293. 

83  Cf .  also  Mach,  Mechanik,  pp.  374-379 ;  Mechanics,  p_  p.  343,  348. 

84  Cf.  also  Mach,  Die  Principled  der  Wdrmelehre,  2d  ed.,  Leipsic,  1900, 
PP.  96-97. 

85  Cf.  Mach,  Mechanik,  pp.  440-453;  Mechanics,  pp.  403-420. 

86  M.  Cantor,  op.  cit.,  pp.  549-551. 


432  THE  MONIST. 

burg  in  1744  to  become  Director,  of  the  Mathematical  Class  of 
Frederick  the  Great's  reformed  Academy  of  Sciences  at  Berlin. 
In  1727  Euler  met  Daniel  Bernoulli  and  was  stimulated  by  him  to  an 
investigation  on  geodesic  lines.8?  The  letters  addressed  by  Daniel 
Bernoulli  to  Euler — those  from  Euler  to  Bernoulli  are  unfortunately 
lost —  from  1726  to  1755  have  been  published  in  P.  H.  Fuss's  Cor- 
respondancc  mathematique  et  physique  de  quelques  cclebres  gco- 
nietres  du  XVIIIicme  siecle.^  From  this  correspondence  we  will 
now  make  the  extracts  which  concern  our  present  subject. 

In  a  letter  to  Euler  of  January  28th,  1741,  Daniel  Bernoulli 
asked  whether  it  was  not  Euler's  opinion  that  orbits  about  centers 
of  force  could  be  deduced  by  an  isoperimetrical  method.89  As  we 
have  said,  Euler's  replies  are  lost.  In  a  letter  of  December  12,  1742, 
Bernoulli  has  some  further  remarks  on  the  same  subject  ;9°  and  in  a 

87  M.  Cantor,  op.  cit.,  p.  843. 

88  St.  Petersburg,  1843,  vol.  ii,  pp.  407-655.     In  these  letters  there  is  fre- 
quently mention  of  isoperimetrical  problems,  but  the  first  mention  of  a  mechan- 
ical problem  treated  by  an  isoperimetrical  method  is  on  pp.  456-457    (letter 
of  March  7,  1739)  where  the  elastic  curve,  which  requires  a  certain  integral 
which  represents  the  "potential  vis  viva"  to  be  a  maximum,  since  Bernoulli 
thinks  "that  an  elastic  lamina  which  takes  a  certain  curvature  of  itself  will 
bend  in  such  a  way  that  the  vis  viva  will  be  a  minimum,  since  otherwise  the 
lamina  would  move,"  is  referred  to  (other  references  are  given  on  pp.  468- 
469,  506-507,  512-514,  533-534.  536-537)-    To  this  apparently  refers  what  Ber- 
noulli (p.  534)  calls  an  a  priori  method — a  speculation  which  contrasts  oddly 
with  the  passages  quoted  below  which  are  rather  anti-"metaphysical."     The 
first  occurrence  of  a  reference  to  a  dynamical  problem  to  be  treated  by  an 
isoperimetrical  method  is  that  given  below. 

It  was  Daniel  Bernoulli  who  recommended  that  Bousquet  of  Geneva 
should  be  chosen  as  the  printer  of  Euler's  "masterly"  (herrlichen)  treatise  on 
the  isoperimetrical  method — the  Methodus  printed  in  1744  (letter  of  Feb.  9, 
1743;  ibid.,  p.  521;  cf.  pp.  524-525  (see  extract  below),  528,  529,  533  (see 
extract  below),  541,  550,  553,  578).  In  a  letter  of  September  4,  1743,  Bernoulli 
(ibid.,  p.  536)  says:  "I  regret  that  I  could  not  read  through  your  additions 
to  the  treatise  on  isoperimeters ;  but  I  have  just  (fugitive  oculo)  glanced  at 
them."  This  is  important  in  view  of  Euler's  account  (section  XII  below)  of 
the  date  and  circumstances  under  which  these  additions  were  made  and 
printed. 

'  "Von  E\v.  mochte  vernehmen,  ob  Sie  nicht  meinen,  dass  man  die  orbitas 
circa  centra  virium  konne  methodo  isoperimetrica,  wie  auch  die  figuram  terrae 
pro  theoria  Newtoniana  herausbringen"  (Fuss,  Correspondance,  vol.  ii,  p.  468). 

°"Man  kann  die  principia  maximorum  et  minimorum  nicht  genugsam 
ausforschen;  die  trajectoriae  circa  centrum  virium,  vel  circa  plura  centra 
virium,  miissen  gleichfalls  per  methodurn  isoperimetricorum  konnen  solviret 
werden,  obschon  man  das  maximum  vel  minimum,  quod  natura  affectat,  nicht 
einsiehet.  Es  haben  also  Ew.  einen  grossen  Nutzen  dadurch  geschafft,  dass 
Sie  die  methodum  isoperimetricorum  so  weit  perfectionnirt  haben.  Meiner 
Meinung  nach  ist  dieses  argumentum  inter  omnia  pure  analytica  utilissimum, 
und  ist  dieses  ein  wahres  Exempel,  dass  vel  sola  propositio  problematis,  wenn 
man  auch  die  Solution  nicht  hatte,  saepe  maxima  laude  digna  sey"  (ibid.,  p. 
513). 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  433 

letter  of  April  23,  1743,  speakss1  with  praise  of  Euler's  great  treatise 
on  the  Isoperimetrical  Method,  suggests  the  addition  of  a  treatment 
of  the  problem  of  the  elastic  curve  and  others  like  it,  and  then  com- 
ments on  Euler's  discovery  that  §v.ds  is  a  minimum  for  central 
orbits,  that  Euler  has  obviously  communicated  to  him  without  proof, 
as  follows: 

"The  observation  about  trajectories  that  fjv.ds  must  be  a  maxi- 
mum or  minimum  appears  to  me  very  beautiful  and  important ;  but 
I  cannot  see  how  this  principle  is  demonstrated.  Please  let  me  know 
whether  the  principle  extends  to  trajectories  about  many  centers  of 
forces.  Perhaps  it  is  only  an  observation  a  posteriori,  owing  to  a 
discovery  you  may  have  made  that  the  trajectories  have  this  prop- 
erty, and  you  may  not  have  been  able  to  demonstrate  it  a  priori" 

In  a  letter  of  September  4,  1743,  Bernoulli  writes  :92 

81  Wegen  Ew.  herrlichen  Tractat  de  isoperimetricis  werde  ich  yorlaufig 
mit  demselben  reden ;  Sie  belieben  nnr  denselben  fertig  zu  halten.  Sie  konn- 
ten  das  problema  de  elastica  hac  methodo  invenienda  und  andere  dergleichen 
noch  beyfiigen.  Ich  sehe  leicht,  dass  man  die  curvaturam  catenae  et  laminae 
elasticae  oscillantis  auch  darin  reduciren  kann ;  auf  den  modum  aber  bin  ich 
noch  nicht  bedacht  gewesen.  Die  meisten  ciirvas  mechanicas  wird  man  auch 
dahin  reduciren  konnen.  Die  Observation  von  den  trajectoriis,  dass  ^v.ds 
ein  maximum  oder  minimum  seyn  miisse,  diinkt  mich  sehr  schon  und  von 
grosser  Wichtigkeit ;  ich  sehe  aber  die  Demonstration  dieses  principii  nicht  ein. 
Ew.  belieben  mir  zu  melden,  ob  sich  solches  auch  ad  trajectorias  circa  plura 
centra  virium  erstrecke.  Vielleicht  ist  es  nur  eine  observatio  a  posteriori,  in- 
dem  Sie  angemerkt  haben,  dass  die  trajectoriae  diese  proprietatem  haben,  ohne 
solche  a  priori  recht  demonstriren  zu  konnen"  (ibid.,  pp.  524-525). 

02  "Aus  Dero  Brief  ersehe  ich,  dass  ich  in  meiner  Conjectur  mich  nicht 
betrogen,  wenn  ich  gesagt  habe,  dass  Dero  Observation  circa  orbitas  plane- 
tarum,  in  quibus  ^v.ds  vel  \v.v.dt  ein  minimum  ist,  vielleicht  nur  a  poste- 
riori sey  gemacht  worden ;  denn  nach  meinen  principiis  kann  ich  solches  a 
priori  nicht  einsehen.  Der  Herr  Clairaut  schreibt,  dass  solches  auch  schon 
von  einem  Englander  sey  remarquirt  worden.  Es  scheint,  dass  dieses  nicht 
sowohl  ein  principium,  als  eine  proprietas  sey,  gleich  wie  es  eine  proprietas 
ist  elasticae,  dass  sie  das  maximum  solidum  generirt.  Doch  hab  ich  nicht 
untersucht,  ob  die  idea  maximi  solidi  die  elasticam  in  omni  extensione  be- 
greife.  Sie  konnen  mich  dieser  Miihe  entheben,  denn  ich  weiss,  dass  Sie  alle 
dergleichen  Untersuchungen  allbereits  gemacht  haben.  Von  meinem  principio 
a  priori,  dass  die  elastica  das  \  ds/rr  ein  minimum  formire,  hab  ich  mit 
vieler  Erkenntlichkeit  ersehen,  aber  zugleich  mit  Beschamung,  dass  Sie  in 
Ihrem  supplemento  so  honorificam  mentionem  thun.  Dieses  principium  gehet 
auch  an  in  laminis  inaequaliter  elasticis,  wenn  man  macht  $eds/r.r  ein  mini- 
mum. Die  laminae  naturaliter  non  rectae  erfordern  zwar  einen  andern  calculum, 
aber  keine  andere  methodum ;  wenn  aber  die  laminae  proprio  pondere  zu- 
gleich incurvirt  werden,  so  ist  es  schwer,  das  maximum  oder  minimum  quod 
natura  affectat  zu  determiniren.  Ich  muthmaasse,  dass  man  allhier  muss  ad 
maxima  maximorum  recurriren,  wenn  zweyerley  Considerationen  zusammen 
kommen.  Quaeatur  brevitatis  gratia  curva  AC,  quam  lamina  naturaliter  recta 
AB  et  uniformis  proprio  solo  pondere  incurvata  accipiet :  f ragt  sich,  ob  nicht 
curva  AC  talis  seyn  konnte,  dass  inter  omnes  eiusdem  longitudinis,  inter  eos- 
demque  terminos  positas  curyas,  eandemque  f  ds/rr  habentes,  das  centrum 
gravitatis  infimum  locum  obtineat.  Wir  haben  Beide  diese  curvam  directe 
determinirt;  fragt  sich  also,  ob  man  ex  hoc  principio  eandem  curvam  finden 


434  THE  MONIST. 

"From  your  letter  I  see  that  I  was  not  mistaken  in  my  conjecture 
that  your  observation  that  §v.ds  or  fv.v.dt  is  a  minimum  for  the 
orbits  of  the  planets  was  perhaps  only  made  a  posteriori ;  for  I  can- 
not see  this  a  priori  by  the  light  of  my  principles.  M.  Clairaut  writes 
that  this  property  has  also  been  noticed  by  an  Englishman.  It 
appears  that  this  is  not  so  much  a  principle  as  a  property,  just 
as  it  is  a  property  of  the  elastic  curve  to  generate  the  maximum 
solid.  Still  I  have  not  investigated  whether  the  idea  of  the  maximum 
solid  includes  that  of  the  elastic  curve  in  all  its  extension . . . . " 

And  in  a  letter  of  December  25,  1743,  Bernoulli  writes  :$3 

"I  doubt  whether  one  can  ever  show  a  priori  that  the  elastic 
curve  must  generate  the  maximum  solid  ;  I  consider  this  as  a  property 
which  is  shown  by  calculation  and  that  nobody  could  have  foreseen 
from  first  principles — as  little  as  the  identity  of  the  isochrone  and 
the  brachystochrone.  Such  properties  are,  as  it  were,  discovered 
through  accident  by  our  reason,  and  I  consider  the  property  ob- 
served, that  in  orbits  fu.ds  is  a  minimum,  to  be  on  this  level.  I 
was  confirmed  in  this  opinion  by  learning  that  you  only  observed 
this  property  a  posteriori  and  never  would  have  found  it  if  you  had 
not  determined  the  orbit  by  other  means." 

Lastly,  Bernoulli's  anti-"metaphysical"  tendency  is  still  more 
strongly  shown  in  a  passage94  of  a  letter  to  Euler  of  April  29,  1747: 

"Herr  Ramspeck  has  written  to  my  father  that  you  are  engaged 
in  various  public  metaphysical  controversies.  You  really  ought  not 
to  meddle  with  such  matters,  for  from  you  we  expect  only  sublime 
things,  and  it  is  not  possible  to  excel  in  metaphysics." 

Euler,  we  know,  had  a  strong  reverence  for  "metaphysics"  and 

wiirde.  Der  calculus  aber  wird  ohne  Zweifel  weitlaufig  seyn,  und  bin  ich  von 
diesem  principio  nicht  convincirt,  so  dass  Ew.  sich  schwerlich  die  Miihe  werden 
gebenwollen  meine  Conjectur  zu  untersuchen.  Wenn  solche  aber  richtigware, 
wiirde  es,  wie  ich  glaube,  leicht  seyn,  schier  aller  curvarum  maxima  et  minima 
a  priori  anzuzeigen"  (ibid.,  pp.  533-534)- 

83  "Ich  zweifle  ob  man  jemals  a  priori  werde  zeigen  konnen,  dass  die 
elastica  miisse  maximum  solidum  generiren ;  ich  betrachte  solches  als  eine 
Proprietat,  die  der  calculus  ausweiset,  und  die  kein  Mensch  ex  principiis  novis 
jemals  wiirde  haben  konnen  vorhersehen,  eben  so  wenig  als  die  identitatem 
isochronae  et  brachystochronae.  Dergleichen  proprietates  sind  ratione  nostri 
gleichsam  accidental,  und  auf  diesen  Fuss  betrachte  ich  auch  die  observatam 
proprietatem  orbitarum,  in  quibus  [u.ds  ein  minimum  macht,  worin  ich  um 
so  viel  mehr  confirmirt  werde,  als  ich  errathen,  dass  Sie  diese  proprietatem 
nur  a  posteriori  observirt  haben  und  niemals  wiirden  gefunden  haben,  wenn 
Sie  nicht  die  orbitas  aliunde  determinirt  hatten"  (ibid.,  p.  543). 

14  "Herr  Ramspeck  hat  meinem  Vater  geschrieben,  dass  Sie  in  unter- 
schiedenen  controversiis  metaphysicis  publicis  stehen.  Sie  sollten  sich  nicht 
iiber  dergleichen  Materien  einlassen;  denn  von  Ihnen  erwartet  man  nichts  als 
sublime  Sachen,  und  es  ist  nicht  moglich  in  jenen  zu  excelliren"  (ibid.,  p.  621). 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  435 

consequently  attached  to  Maupertuis's  a  priori  speculations  a  value 
far  above  his  own  discovery.  We  shall  see  later  that,  in  papers 
published  among  the  Mcmoires  of  the  Berlin  Academy,  he  empha- 
sizes, as  he  apparently  did  to  Daniel  Bernoulli,  the  fact  that  he  had 
only  discovered  the  minimal  condition  satisfied  by  orbital  motion  in 
an  a  posteriori  manner,  as  if  this  was  rather  a  demerit.  Nowadays 
we  would  say  that  Euler's  great  caution  in,  for  example,  insisting,  in 
his  Methodus,  that  the  v  in 

fv.ds 

is  to  be  expressed  in  terms  of  ^  by  the  principle  of  vis  viva,  so  that 
his  minimal  principle  cannot  be  extended  to  the  case  of  motion  in 
a  resisting  medium,  where  the  principle  of  vis  viva  does  not  hold,  and, 
in  later  publications,  the  careful  enumeration  of  cases  when  testing 
Maupertuis's  statical  principle,  are  merits.  But  the  following  ex- 
tract from  the  first  appendix  on  elastic  curves  to  the  Methodus  of 
1744  proves  that  more  general  "metaphysical"  ideas  were  by  no 
means  foreign  to  Euler: 

"For  since  the  plan  of  the  universe  is  the  most  perfect  possible 
and  the  work  of  the  wisest  possible  creator,  nothing  happens  which 
has  not  some  maximal  or  minimal  property,  and  therefore  there  is 
no  doubt  but  that  all  the  effects  in  nature  can  be  equally  well  deter- 
mined from  final  causes  by  the  aid  of  the  method  of  maxima  and 
minima  as  from  the  efficient  causes."95 

x. 

We  will  now  return  to  the  publications  of  the  Berlin  Academy. 
The  only  paper  concerning  us  here  in  the  Histoire  for  1747, 

95  "Cum  enim  Mundi  universi  fabrica  sit  perfectissima,  atque  a  Creatpre 
sapientissimo  absoluta,  nihil  omnino  in  mundo  contingit,  in  quo  non  maximi 
minimive  ratio  quaepiam  eluceat;  quamobrem  dubium  prorsus  est  nullum, 
quin  omnes  Mundi  effectus  ex  causis  finalibus,  ope  Methodi  maximorum  et 
minimorum,  aeque  feliciter  determinari  queant,  atque  ex  ipsis  causis  efficienti- 
bus,  Methodus,  p.  245,  and  cf.  section  XII  below.  (See  Ostzvalds  Klassiker, 
No.  175,  p.  18.  Cf.  Mach,  Mechanik,  p.  485;  Mechanics,^.  455.  Cf.  also 
E.  Diihring,  Kritische  Geschichte  dcr  allgemeinen  Principien  der  Mechanik, 
3d  ed.,  Leipsic,  1887,  pp.  293-294,  296-299,  385-400).  These  reflections  of 
Diihring's  are  on  the  effects  of  philosophy  on  mechanics  and  Lagrange's  anti- 
"metaphysical"  tendencies.  Lagrange's  own  words  are  (Mechanique  analitique, 
Paris,  1788,  p.  187):  "....as  if  vague  and  arbitrary  denominations  [such  as 
the  least  quantity  of  action}  made  up  the  essential  part  of  the  laws  of  nature 
and  could  by  some  secret  virtue  raise  simple  results  of  the  known  laws  of 

mechanics  to  the  position  of  final  causes";  and  (p.  189)  :  " 1  regard  this 

principle  [of  least  action]  not  as  a  metaphysical  principle  but  as  a  simple  and 
general  result  of  the  laws  of  mechanics." 

On  the  principle  of  least  action  with  Fermat,  Maupertuis,  Euler,  and 
Lagrange,  and  its  effect  on  Gauss,  cf.  Diihring,  op.  cit.,  pp.  100-102,  218-219, 
287-302,  425-430. 


436  THE  MONIST. 

published  in  1749,  is  one  in  the  class  of  speculative  philosophy  by 
Samuel  Formey,96  entitled :  "Examen  de  la  preuve  qu'on  tire  des  fins 
de  la  nature,  pour  etablir  1'existence  de  Dieu" ;  in  which  the  author 
comes,  by  a  rather  different  way,  to  the  same  conclusions  as  Mau- 
pertuis  (1746). 

In  the  Histoire  for  1748,  published  in  1750,  there  are  two  papers 
relating  to  our  subject  by  Euler.0?  The  first  is  entitled :  "Recherches 
sur  les  plus  grands  et  plus  petits  qui  se  trouvent  dans  les  actions 
des  forces,"  and  he  quoted  with  approval  Maupertuis's  memoir  of 
1746,  and  remarked98  that  Maupertuis  had  shown  that  in  the  state 
of  equilibrium  of  bodies,  if  some  small  movement  were  to  happen  to 
them,  the  quantity  of  action  would  be  the  least.  He  himself,  says 
Euler,  had  discovered  a  similar  law  in  the  motion  of  bodies  attracted 
to  one  or  many  centers  of  forces;  in  this  case  §u.ds  expresses  the 
quantity  of  action.  In  statics"  this  principle  has  been  long  recog- 
nized. Thus,  it  is  easy  to  see  that  a  chain  suspended  by  its  ends 
must  take  such  a  figure  that  the  center  of  gravity  of  the  chain  is  as 
low  as  possible ;  and  thus,  if  x  is  the  distance  of  the  element  ds 
from  an  arbitrary  horizontal  plane,  fx.ds  will  be  a  minimum  for 
the  curve  of  the  chain,  and  fjz.ds  is  the  quantity  of  action.100  Many 
other  analogous  cases  were,  according  to  Euler,  treated  by  Mau- 
pertuis; and  Daniel  Bernoulli  remarked  that  the  curve  of  an  elastic 
lamina  has  a  minimal  property,  and  this  view  was  developed  by 
Euler  in  Appendix  i  of  his  Methodus  inveniendi  of  1744.101 

There  are,  then,  two  ways  of  solving  mechanical  problems :  one 
is  the  direct  method,  and  the  other  is,  knowing  the  formula  which 
must  be  a  maximum  or  a  minimum,  by  the  method  of  maxima  and 
minima ;  the  effect  is  determined  by  efficient  causes  and  by  final 
causes  respectively.  But  it  is  often  very  difficult  to  discover  the 
formula  which  must  be  a  maximum  or  a  minimum,  and  by  which  the 
quantity  of  action  is  represented;  and  this  investigation  belongs 

06  Pp.  365-384- 

07  Pp.  149-188  and  189-218. 

08  Ibid.,  p.  150. 

09  Ibid.,  pp.  150-151. 
100  Ibid.,  p.  151. 

101 A  convenient  German  translation  of  this  Appendix,  with  critical  and 
historical  notes  by  H.  Linsenbarth,  was  given  in  No.  175  of  Ostwalds  Klassiker 
(Abhandlungen  uber  das  Glcichgewicht  und  die  Schwingungen  der  ebenen 
elastischen  Kurven  von  Jakob  Bernoulli  (1691,  1694,  1695)  und  Leonh.  Euler 
(1744)).  Very  interesting  are  Euler's  (pp.  18-20)  theological  remarks  and 
references  to  the  frequency  with  which  maximal  and  minimal  problems  ap- 
peared in  the  mechanical  work  of  the  Bernoullis.  (Cf.  section  IX  above.) 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  437 

rather  to  metaphysics  than  to  mathematics.  "I  believe,"  says  Euler,102 
"that  we  are  still  very  far  from  that  degree  of  perfection  where  we 
are  able  to  assign,  for  each  effect  which  nature  produces  the  quantity 
of  action  which  is  the  smallest,  and  deduce  it  from  the  first  prin- 
ciples of  our  knowledge ;  and  that  it  will  be  almost  impossible  to  ar- 
rive at  it  unless  we  discover,  for  a  great  number  of  different  cases, 
the  formulas  which  become  maximal  or  minimal.  Now,  knowing 
the  solutions  with  which  the  direct  method  furnishes  us,  it  will  not 
be  difficult  to  find  a  posteriori  formulas  which  express  the  quantity 
of  action,  and  then  it  will  not  be  so  difficult  to  prove  their  truth  by 
the  known  principles  of  metaphysics."  With  this  end  in  view,  Euler 
investigated  several  problems  as  to  the  curve  formed  by  a  flexible 
string  in  equilibrium. 

Euler10^  arrived  at  the  conclusion  that  the  expression  of  the 
quantity  of  action,  which,  when  supposed  to  be  a  minimum,  gives  the 
figure  of  the  thread,  is  in  perfect  agreement  with  the  Lazv  of  Rest 
published  by  Maupertuis  in  1740. 

Euler's  second  memoir  on  the  principle  of  least  action  in  this 
volume  is  entitled:  "Reflexions  sur  quelques  Loix  generates  de  la 
Nature  qui  s'observent  dans  les  Effets  des  Forces  quelconques."  He 
emphasizesI04  that  he  was  only  led  a  posteriori  to  the  discovery  of 
the  minimum  in  the  case  of  the  equilibrium  of  threads,  and  thenlos 
remarks :  "It  is  the  figure  which  a  fluid  mass,  all  of  whose  particles 
are  attracted  by  any  forces,  which  was  the  principal  object  of  the 
researches  of  M.  de  Maupertuis  in  order  to  discover  the  general  law 
of  rest  in  the  Paris  Memoir es  of  1740.  Thus  I  too  will  consider  a 
fluid  mass,  all  of  whose  particles  are  attracted  to  as  many  fixed 
centers  as  is  wished  by  forces  proportional  to  any  functions  of  the 
distances  to  those  centers,  and  I  will  investigate  the  figure  of  equi- 
librium for  this  mass.  Then  I  will  try  to  discover  what  will  be  a 
maximum  or  a  minimum  in  this  figure,  in  order  to  be  in  a  better 
state  to  determine  what  must  be  understood  by  the  name  of  the 
quantity  of  action  of  the  attracting  forces]  and  afterwards  I  will 
show  by  some  reflections  the  great  importance  of  this  quantity  in 
all  researches  concerning  the  effects  produced  by  any  forces."  The 
expression  discovered  in  this  way  was  again  found  to  agree  with 
Maupertuis's  law  of  1740. 

102  Op.  cit.,  p.  152. 

103  Ibid.,  p.  180. 
104/Zmf.,  p.  190. 

105  Ibid.,  p.  191 ;  cf .  p.  190. 


438  THE  MONIST. 


XL 

There  is  nothing  relating  to  the  principle  of  least  action,  nor 
to  mechanics  (except  in  astronomy)  in  the  Berlin  Histoire  for  1749 
(published  in  1751)  ;  but  in  that  for  1750  (published  in  1752)  there 
is106  an  "Expose  concernant  1'examen  de  la  lettre  de  M.  de  Leibnitz, 
alleguee  par  M.  le  Prof.  Koenig10?  dans  les  mois  de  Mars,  1751,  des 
Actes  de  Leipzig,108,  a  1'occasion  du  principe  de  la  moindre  action" 
by  Euler,  I09,  with  the  note:  "As  will  easily  be  seen  by  reading  this 
memoir,  it  is  one  of  those  whose  publication  may  not  be  delayed." 

Konig  had  denied  the  validity  of  the  principle  in  the  case  of 
equilibrium,  and  indicated  some  cases  in  which  what,  according  to 
the  principle,  ought  to  be  a  minimum  really  reduces  to  nothing.  But, 
says  Euler,110  "this  objection  is  not  of  great  importance,  since  it 
is  sufficiently  recognized  in  the  calculus  of  maxima  and  minima 
that  it  can  often  happen  what  is  a  minimum  vanishes  entirely.  But 
although  that  may  be  so  in  certain  cases  it  by  no  means  results  that 
one  ought  to  extend  it  to  all  cases  of  equilibrium,  as  always  neces- 
sarily happening  in  that  state ;  on  the  contrary,  there  are  numberless 
cases  in  which  this  quantity  of  action  is  not  zero  but  is  really  a 
minimum ;  and  this  puts  beyond  doubt  that  the  aim  of  Nature  is  not 
the  nullity  of  action,  but  its  minimity."  Then  Euler  quotes  the 
example  of  the  catenary,  and  says  that  the  quantity  of  action  reduces 

106  Pp.  52-64. 

107Johann  Samuel  Konig  (1712-1757);  Cf.  M.  Cantor,  op.  cit.,  pp.  599- 
601.  Konig  was  a  pupil  of  Johann  Bernoulli's  at  the  same  time  as  Maupertuis. 
(Mayer,  op.  cit.,  pp.  17-18). 

108  "De  Universal!  Principle-  Aequilibrii  et  motus  in  Vi  viva  reperto  deque 
nexu  inter  Vim  vivam  et  Actionem  utriusque  Minimo"   (Nova  Acta  Erudi- 
torum,  1751,  pp.  125-135,  144,  162-176).     Konig  affirms  that  equilibrium  is  a 
result  of  the  nullity  of  action  and  vis  viva  (pp.  126,  164)  that  in  some  cases 
the  action  is  a  maximum,  and  this  would  hardly  be  reconcilable  with  Mau- 
pertuis's  proof  of  the  Creator's  wisdom  (pp.  126,  165)  ;  and  that  since  action 
is  vis  viva  into  the  time,  the  principle  is  that  vis  viva  is  a  minimum^  (p.  127). 
Konig,  like  a  thorough  Leibnizian,  praises  the  theorem  of  vis  viva  highly 
("Censeo  itaque,  Theoremate  Virium  vivarum  fundamentum  universae  Me- 
chanicae  contineri,"  p.  169),  and  deduces  statistics  from  it.    The  extract  from 
the  letter  of  Leibniz's  is  given  quite  at  the  end  (p.  176)  and  is:  "L' Action  n'est 
point  ce  que  vous  penses,  la  consideration  du  terns  y  entre ;  elle  est  comme  le 
produit  de  la  masse  par  le  terns,  ou  du  terns  par  la  force  vive.    J'ai  remarque 
que   dans   les   modifications    des   mouvemens    elle   devient   ordinairement   un 
Maximum,  ou  un  Minimum.     On  en  peut^deduire  plusieurs  propositions  de 
grande  consequence ;   elle  pourroit  servir  a  determiner  les  courbes  que  de- 
crivent  les  corps  attires  a  un  ou  plusieurs  centres.    Je  voulois  traiter  de  ces 
choses  entr'autres  dans  le  seconde  partie  de  ma  Dynamique,  que  j'ai  supprimee; 
le  mauvais  accueil,  que  le  prejuge  a  fait  a  la  premiere,  m'ayant  degoute." 

109  As  we  learn  from  a  note  on  p.  63  of  the  Histoire  for  1750. 

.  53- 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  439 

to  the  distance  of  the  center  of  gravity  of  the  chain  from  the  center 
of  the  earth;  and111  Daniel  Bernoulli's  and  his  own  researches  on 
elastic  curves. 

As  regards  dynamics,  Konig  quoted  from  a  supposed  letter 
written  by  Leibniz  to  Hermann,  in  which  "action"  was  defined  as 
Maupertuis  defined  it  and  the  property  of  being  "ordinarily  a  maxi- 
mum or  a  minimum"  in  dynamical  problems  remarked.  Konig 
could  not  produce  the  original  nor  could  the  original  be  found  by 
officials.  It  is  not  interesting  now  to  follow  the  controversy  much 
further.  Konig  did  not  charge  Maupertuis  with  plagiarism;112  but, 
since  the  principle  was  considered  by  Maupertuis  and  others  to  be 
of  the  greatest  possible  importance  and  to  reflect  great  credit  on 
Maupertuis,  its  discoverer,  the  Berlin  Academy,  of  which  Maupertuis 
was  president,  took  up  the  matter  with  great  zeal,  and  concluded, 
like  Euler's  report,  that,  on  internal  and  external  evidences,  the 
fragment  of  the  letter  was  forged,  either  to  injure  Maupertuis  or 
to  exaggerate,  by  a  pious  fraud,  the  merits  of  Leibniz.  "3  The  re- 
sult was  an  unjust  expulsion  of  Konig  from  the  Berlin  Academy, 
and  the  consequent  culmination  of  Voltaire's  ill-feeling  towards 
Maupertuis.  "4 

XII. 

To  return  to  the  Plistoire  for  1750.  To  the  literature  of  the 
controversy  also  belongs  a  "Lettre  de  M.  Euler  a  M.  [Jean  Bernard] 
Merian"  of  September  3,  1752.IIs  Nowadays,  the  only  interesting 
part  of  this  letter  is  where  Euler116  gives  some  details  about  the  publi- 
cation of  his  Methodus  inveniendi.  The  defenders  of  Konig  stated  that 
they  knew  the  Methodus  had  been  in  the  publisher's  hands  at  Lau- 


.  54- 
.  60. 

113  Ibid.,  p.  62. 

114  On  the  Konig  incident,  see  La  Beaumelle,  op.  cit.,  pp.  139-141,  143-145, 
150-167,  and,  on  Voltaire's  part  in  it,  pp.  167  et  seq.   Further  du  Bois-Reymond, 
op.  cit.,  pp.  35-36,  47,  50-66.     It  is  now  known  that  the  fragment  of  Leibniz's 
letter  was  probably  genuine,  and  part  of  a  letter  to  Varignon  ;  Cf.  ibid.,  pp. 
56-57,  and  the  references  to  Gerhardt's  paper  in  M.  Cantor,  op.  cit.,  p.  599. 

Even  in  1877,  Mayer  (op.  cit.,  p.  19)  said  that  the  letter  was  without 
doubt  forged;  but  Helmholtz  in  1887  (op.  cit.}  showed  that  its  genuineness 
was  probable. 

It  appears  that  Euler  only  made  one  separately  printed  contribution  to 
the  discussion  on  Konig'  s  dissertation  ;  it  is  entitled  :  "Dissertatio  de  principio 
minimae  actionis  una  cum  exaniinatione  objectionum  Cl.  Prof.  Konig  contra 
hoc  principium  factorum,"  Berlin,  1783.  We  have  not  seen  this  work,  but  only 
quote  it  from  the  Bibliography  in  Fuss's  Correspondance,  vol.  i,  p.  xciv. 

™Ibid.,  pp.  520-532. 

™Ibid.t  pp.  525-526. 


44O  THE  MONIST. 

sanne  since  1743,  a  circumstance  which  would  give  Euler  priority 
over  Maupertuis.  This,  says  Euler,  is  correct  in  so  far  as  it  con- 
cerns the  treatise  itself,  which  he  had  finished  some  years  before  it 
appeared,  but  he  only  made  the  additions  since  he  had  sent  the 
manuscript  to  Lausanne,  and  only  shortly  before  the  publication  of 
the  book  towards  the  end  of  1744.  Further,  he  had  communicated 
this  supplement  to  nobody  before  printing  it. 

"When,"  says  Euler,1 1?  "I  used  the  method  of  maxima  and 
minima  to  define  the  trajectories  which  are  described  by  bodies  at- 
tracted by  any  central  force,  I  do  not  pretend  to  have  been  beyond 
what  MM.  Bernoulli  and  others  have  done  when  they  determined 
by  the  help  of  the  same  method  the  curvature  of  the  catenary,  that  of 
a  piece  of  linen  filled  with  liquid,  and  other  curves  of  the  same  kind. 
Such  investigations  only  furnish  particular  principles  which  can 
hardly  be  extended  further  than  the  cases  to  which  they  are  applied. 
On  the  other  hand,  it  is  a  question  here  of  a  universal  principle,  from 
which  all  the  former  principles  should  result,  and  which  can  be  re- 
garded as  a  Law  established  in  all  the  phenomena  of  nature ;  which 
would  render  its  discussion  less  the  part  (du  ressort)  of  Mathe- 
matics than  of  Metaphysics,  on  the  principles  of  which  this  doctrine 
should  be  founded.  Also,  although  for  long  people  have  not  doubted 
that,  in  all  natural  effects,  there  is  a  maximal-minimal  principle  which 
determines  them,  nobody  before  the  Illustrious  President  of  our 
Academy  has  even  suspected  in  what  elements  this  principle  was 
contained  and  how  it  could  be  accommodated  to  all  cases.118  As 

117  Ibid.,  pp.  526-527. 

118  Cf.  Methodus,  pp.  309,  320.    The  actual  quotations  are:  (i)  "Quoniam 
omnes  naturae  effectus  sequuntur  quandam  maximi  minimive  legem;  dubium 
est  nullum,  quin  in  lineis  curvis,  quas  corpora  projecta,  si  a  viribus  quibus- 
cunque  sollicitentur,  describunt,  quaepiam  maximi  minimive  proprietas  locum 
habeat.    Quaenam  autem  sit  ista  proprietas,  ex  principiis  metaphysicis  a  priori 
defmire  non  tarn  facile  videtur :   cum  autem  has  ipsa  curvas,  ope   Methodi 
directae,  determinare  liceat;  hinc,  debita  adhibita  attentione,  id  ipsum,  quod 
in  istis  curvis  est  maximum  yel  minimum,  concludi  poterit.     Spectari  autem 
potissimum  debet  effectus  a  viribus  sollicitantibus  oriundus;  qui  cum  in  motu 
corporis  genito  consistat,  veritati  consentaneum  videtur  hunc  ipsum  motum, 
seu  potius  aggregatum  omnium  motuum  qui  in  corpore  projecto  insunt,  mini- 
mum esse  debere.     Quae  conclusio  etsi  non  satis  confirmata  videatur,  tamen, 
si  earn  cum  veritate  jam  a  priori  nota  consentire  ostendero,  tantum  conseque- 
tur  pondus,  ut  omnia  dubia  quae  circa  earn  suboriri  queant  penitus  evanescant. 
Quin-etiam  cum  ejus  veritas  fuerit  evicta,   facilius  erit  in  intimas   Naturae 
leges  atque  causes  finales   inquirere ;   hocque  assertum  firmissimis   rationibus 

corroborare." (2)  "Tarn  late  ergo  hoc  principium  patet,  ut  solus  motus 

a  resistentia  medii  perturbatus  excipiendus  videatur;  cujus  quidem  exceptionis 
ratio  facile  perspicitur,  propterea  quod  hoc  casu  corpus  per  varias  vias   ad 
eundum   locum   perveniens   non   eandem   acquirit   celeritatem.      Quamobrem, 
sublata  omni  resistentia  in  motu  corporum  projectorum,  perpetuo  haec  con- 
stans  proprietas  locum  habebit,  ut  summa  omnium  motuum  elementarium  sit 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  44! 

regards  myself,  I  only  knew  in  a  sure  manner  a  posteriori  the  prin- 
ciple I  used  to  determine  trajectories ;  and  I  have  ingenuously  con- 
fessed that  I  was  not  in  a  position  to  establish  its  truth  in  another 
manner.  All  that  I  have  done  is  to  deduce  from  it  the  same  curves 
that  are  commonly  found  by  the  direct  method,  starting  from  the 
principles  of  mechanics.  I  have  not  even  dared  to  extend  its  use 
unless  I  could  justify  by  calculation  its  agreement  with  known  prin- 
ciples. And  that  is  what  has  led  me  to  separate  from  this  principle 
motions  in  a  resisting  medium  and  other  more  complicated  ones ; 
for  no  way  presented  itself  to  my  mind  of  discovering  the  truth 
with  regard  to  these  motions." 

Among  the  Memoircs  in  the  Class  of  Speculative  Philosophy  in 
the  same  volume  (1750)  of  the  Histoire,  are  two  by  Merian1^  en- 
titled: "Dissertation  ontologique  sur  1'Action,  la  Puissance  et  la 
Liberte,"  and  "Seconde  Dissertation  sur  TAction,  la  Puissance  et  la 
Liberte";  in  the  first  of  which120  Maupertuis's  explanation,  in  the 
Essai  de  Cosmologie,  of  the  generation  of  the  idea  of  motive  force 
is  quoted. 

XIII. 

In  the  Berlin  Histoire  for  1751,  published  1753,  there  are  five 
memoirs  we  shall  have  to  notice,  and  all  of  the  Class  of  Mathe- 
matics.121 

The  first  is  by  Euler,122  and  is  entitled:  "Harmonic  entre  les 
Principes  generaux  de  Repos  de  Mouvement  de  M.  de  Maupertuis." 
Both  principles  of  Maupertuis  (of  1740  and  1744)  rest,  says  Euler, 
on  the  same  foundation,  so  that  if  one  is  proved,  the  other  cannot  be 

minima.  Neque  vero  haec  proprietas  in  motu  unius  corporis  tantum  cernetur, 
sed  etiam  in  motu  plurium  corporum  conjunctim;  quae  quompdocunque  in 
se  invicem  agant,  tamen  semper  sunima  omnium  motuum  est  minima.  Quod, 
cum  hujusmodi  motus  difficulter  ad  calculum  revocentur,  facilius  ex  primis 
principiis  intelligitur,  quam  ex  consensu  calculi  secundum  utramque  Metho- 
dum  instituti.  Quoniam  enim  corpora,  ob  inertiam,  omni  status  mutationi 
reluctantur ;  viribus  sollicitantibus  tamparum  obtemperabunt,  quam  fieri  potest, 
siquidem  sint  libera ;  ex  quo  efficitur,  ut,  in  motu  genito,  effectus  a  viribus 
ortus  minor  esse  debeat,  quam  si  ullo  alio  modo  corpus  vel  corpora  fuissent 
promota.  Cujus  ratipcinii  vis,  etiamsi  nondum  satis  perspiciatur;  tamen,  quia 
cum  veritate  congruit,  non  dubito  quin,  ope  principiorum  sanioris  Metaphy- 
sicae,  ad  majorem  evidentiam  evehi  queat;  quod  negotium  aliis,  qui  Metaphy- 
sicam  prositentur,  relinquo." 

119  Pp.  459-485  and  486-516. 

120  Ibid.,  p.  479. 

121  In  this  volume,  the  memoirs  in  the  Classes  of  Experimental  Philosophy 
and  Mathematics  are  paged  (pp.  1-356)  separately  from  those  in  the  Classes 
of  Speculative  Philosophy  and  of  Belles  Lettres  (pp.  1-154). 

m  Pp.  169-198. 


442  THE  MONIST. 

doubted.  Now,  Maupertuis  and  Euler  had  established  the  truth  of 
the  law  of  rest  of  1740  by  a  multitude  of  different  cases.  Euler, 
then,  first  deduced  the  principle  of  motion  from  that  of  rest,12^  and 
then12*  showed  that  all  the  elementary  theorems  of  statics  follow 
readily  from  the  law  of  rest. 

The  nerve  of  Euler's  investigation  is  the  deduction  of  the  prin- 
ciple of  least  action  from  the  law  of  rest.  Euler  I25  called  the  in- 
tegral fV.dv,  where  V  is  a  central  force  acting  on  the  body  M  and 
v  is  the  distance  from  M  to  any  fixed  point  in  the  direction  of  V,  the 
effort  (effort),  so  that  Maupertuis's  law  is  that  the  sum  of  all  the 
efforts  is  a  maximum  or  a  minimum. 

"What  is  more  natural,"  exclaims  Euler,126  "than  to  maintain 
that  this  same  principle  of  equilibrium  should  also  subsist  in  the 
movement  of  bodies  under  like  forces?  For  if  the  intention  of 
nature  is  to  economize  the  sum  of  the  efforts  as  much  as  possible, 
this  intention  must  extend  also  to  movements,  provided  that  we 
take  the  efforts,  not  merely  as  they  subsist  in  an  instant,  but  in  all 
the  instants  together  for  which  the  movement  lasts.  Thus,  if  the 
sum  of  the  efforts  is  <£  for  any  instant  of  the  motion,  then,  putting 
dt  for  the  element  of  the  time,  the  integral  f3?.dt  must  be  a  mini- 
mum. If  then,  for  the  case  of  equilibrium  the  quantity  3>  must  be  a 
minimum,  the  same  laws  of  nature  seem  to  exact  that,  for  motion 
f®.dt  should  be  the  smallest. 

"Now  it  is  precisely  in  this  formula  that  the  other  principle  of 
M.  de  Maupertuis,  concerning  motion,  is  contained,  however  differ- 
ent it  may  appear  at  the  first  glance.  To  show  this  agreement,  I 
have  only  to  remark  that  when  a  body  moves  under  the  action  of  the 
forces  V,  V,  V",.  .  .  .,  the  effort  <3>  to  which  the  body  is  subject  ex- 
presses at  the  same  time  the  vis  viva  of  the  body  —  the  product  of 
the  mass  M  of  the  body  and  the  square  of  its  velocity  (M)."  Thus 
the  formula  which  must  be  a  minimum  is 


Where  v,  v'  ,  v",  .  .  .  .  ,  are  the  distances  of  M  from  the  centers 

123  On  pp.  181-182,  Euler  remarked  that,  if  we  wish,  inversely,  to  deduce 
the  principle  of  rest  from  that  of  motion,  "we  must  suppose  the  motion  in- 
finitely small,  and  this  causes  great  obscurities  (brou'illeries)  in  the  conside- 
ration of  infinitely  small  velocities  and  of  the  spaces  which  are  described  in 
an  infinitely  small  time. 

124/ZnU,  pp.  183-193. 

125  Ibid.,  p.  174. 

126  Ibid.  p.  175. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  443 

of  forces  V,  V,  V",  .  .  .  .  ,  which  are  functions  of  these  distances, 
Euler12?  gets  the  equation 

Mu2  =  const  -  5  J*  .  dv  -  const  -  <E>  ; 

and:128  "the  constant  does  not  disturb  this  harmony  between  the 
effort  <3>  and  the  vis  viva  M.w2  of  the  body;  for  if  fj^.dt  is  a  maxi- 
mum or  a  minimum,  fM.u2.dt  or  fM.u.ds  will  be  so  also,  since 
the  term  f  const  dt  =  const  t  does  not  enter  into  the  consideration 
of  the  maximum  or  minimum.  And,  besides  that,  as  the  effort  <f> 
is  expressed  by  integral  formulae,  it  already  contains  in  itself  any 
constant,  so  that  I  could  have  neglected  this  constant  entirely  and 
simply  put  Mu2  =  -®,  whence  the  identity  would  have  been  more 
evident.  However,  if  we  take  the  above  integrals  on  a  fixed  foot- 
ing (sur  un  pied  fixe'),  so  that  the  effort  <i>  receives  a  determined 
value,  the  addition  of  the  constant  will  be  necessary;  since  the 
velocity  of  the  body  at  a  certain  point  of  its  path  depends  on  the 
initial  velocity,  and  by  this  initial  velocity  the  constant  must  be  de- 
termined in  each  case  proposed.  But,  of  whatever  quantity  it  may 
be,  the  determination  of  the  maximum  or  minimum  is  not  affected." 
Of  course,  as  Mu2  is  equal  to  the  negative  of  <£,  if  fMu2.dt  is  a 
minimum,  f$.dt  will  be  a  maximum,  and  reciprocally. 

Euler12^  then  proved  "the  identity  between  the  effort  and  the 
vis  viva"  for  two  or  more  bodies,  connected  in  any  way  with  one 
another  to  make  a  flexible  body:  the  sum  of  the  vires  vivae  of  all 
the  elements  of  the  body  always  reduces  to  the  sum  of  the  efforts 
to  which  all  the  elements  are  subject  in  the  same  time,  —  in  the  case 
of  two  bodies  of  masses  M  and  N,  distances  to  the1^0  center  of  force 
considered  x  and  y  respectively,  and  the  accelerating  forces  X  (a 
function  of  .v)  and  Y  (a  function  of  y)  respectively, 


remarked  that  there  are  cases  of  equilibrium  in  which 
the  sum  of  the  efforts  is  a  maximum  and1^2  classes  the  cases  of 
equilibrium  as  of  such  natures  that,  if  the  sum  of  efforts  is  a 
minimum,  equilibrium  reestablishes  itself  on  an  infinitely  small  dis- 


.  177. 
128  Ibid.,  p.  178. 
™Ibid.}  pp.  179-181. 

130  Of  course  the  proof  extends  to  as  many  centers  of  force  as  wished. 

131  Ibid.,  p.  194. 

138  Ibid.,  p.  195.    There  is  an  example  of  the  sum  of  efforts  being  a  maxi- 


mum on  pp.  195-196. 


444  THE  MONIST. 

placement  being  given  to  the  system,  whereas,  if  the  sum  is  a  maxi- 
mum, this  is  not  the  case.  ^3 

XIV. 

Euler's  second  paper  in  the  volume  for  1751  is  entitled:  "Sur 
le  Principe  de  la  Moindre  Action. "T34  This  paper  is  concerned  with 
the  opinion  that  there  is  a  minimum  in  the  actions  of  nature,  with 
Aristotle  and  his  school,  Descartes,  Fermat,  Leibniz,1^  Wolff,  Engel- 
hard, s'Gravesande,  and  others,  and  was  occasioned  by  the  Konig 
affair.  It  is  ridiculous,  says  Euler,^6  to  suppose  that  Konig's  frag- 
ment was  written  by  Leibniz,  for  it  attributes  to  Leibniz  a  principle 
opposed  to  that  which  he  adopted  publicly  in  the  case  of  the  motion 
of  light — that  the  product  of  the  path  described  and  the  resistance 
is  a  minimum. 

Referring  to  his  own  discovery  of  the  minimum  of  the  action — 
integral  for  central  orbits,  Euler's?  remarks:  "Besides,  I  had  not 
discovered  this  beautiful  property  a  priori  but  (using  logical  terms) 
a  posteriori,  deducing  after  many  trials  the  formula  which  must  be- 
come a  minimum  in  these  movements;  and,  not  daring  to  give  it 
more  force  than  in  the  case  which  I  had  treated,  I  did  not  believe 
that  I  had  discovered  a  wider  principle:  I  was  content  with  having 
found  this  beautiful  property  in  the  movements  which  take  place 
around  centers  of  forces." 

Euler's  third  paper  in  this  volume  is  entitled:  "Examen  de  la 
Dissertation  de  M.  Le  Professeur  Koenig,  inseree  dans  les  Actes  de 
Leipzig,  pour  le  Mois  de  Mars,  175 1."1^8  In  this  paper  Euler  exam- 
ined Konig's  demonstrations  with  care  and  pronounced  them  to  be 
worthless.  X39 

The  "Essai  d'une  Demonstration  Metaphysique  du  Principe 
general  de  1'Equilibre"  of  Euler,  printed  in  the  same  volume,1 4° 
does  not  mention  Maupertuis's  name,141  and  is  concerned  with  the 
deduction  from  indubitable  axioms  of  the  principle  that,  for  equilib- 

133  Cf .  Mach,  Mechanik,  pp.  70-75 ;  Mechanics,  pp.  69-73. 

134  Loc.  cit.,  pp.  199-218. 

135  Ibid.,  pp.  205-209. 
™Ibid.,v.  209. 
™Ibid.,  p.  214. 

138  Ibid.,  pp.  219-239,  "Additions,"  pp.  240-245. 
159  Ibid.,  p.  220. 
uo  Ibid.,  pp.  246-254. 

141  It  is,  however,  Maupertuis's  "Law  of  Rest"   (Cf.  also  Mayer,  op.  cit., 
P-  23). 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  .445 

rium,  where,  P,  Q, . . . .  are  forces  and  x,  y, . . . .  are  measured  on 
their  respective  lines  of  action, 

/P.rf.r+/Q. </y  +  .... 
is  a  minimum. 

Lastly,  there  is,  in  this  volume  a  paper  by  Nicolas  de  Beguelin,142 
tutor  of  Frederick  the  Great's  nephew  who  was  later  Frederick 
William  II,  entitled :  "Recherches  sur  1'Existence  des  Corps  Durs/'14^ 
in  which  Maupertuis  is  called  a  great  man144  and  the  illustrious 
author  of  the  principle  of  least  action, I45  and  the  other  conclusions 
are  just  what  Maupertuis  would  have  wished. 

xv. 

In  the  Paris  Memoires  for  1749,  the  Chevalier  d'Arcy146  pub- 
lished some  reflections  on  the  principle  of  least  action,  which  he 
had  long  hesitated  to  publish,  but  that  he  did  so  in  the  interests  of 
truth.  D'Arcy  maintained:  (1)  That  the  action  of  a  body  is  not 
proportional  to  m.v.s,  because  this  supposition,  in  a  particular  case, 
leads  to  a  result  contrary  to  that  which  the  laws  of  motion  give; 
(2)  That,  admitting  Maupertuis's  definition  of  action,  the  quantity 
of  it  that  nature  employs  in  each  change  is  not  a  minimum,  and 
that  if  in  some  cases  this  is  so,  the  principle  of  least  action  cannot 
serve  to  prove  it;  (3)  that  Maupertuis's  law  of  equilibrium  that 
Maupertuis  deduced  from  the  principle  of  least  action  is  only  estab- 
lished by  the  introduction  of  a  foreign  and  gratuitous  supposition ; 
(4)  that,  in  general,  whatever  may  be  the  laws  of  nature,  one  could 
always  easily  find  a  function  of  the  masses  and  velocities  which 
would  represent  them  when  it  is  supposed  to  be  a  minimum,  but 
this  property  would  not  be  enough  to  give  the  name  of  action  to 
this  function  nor  to  raise  the  principle  thence  obtained  to  the  rank 
of  a  metaphysical  principle;147  (5)  that,  if  we  define  the  action  of 

143 Lived  from  1714  to  1789.  (Cf.  Berlin  Histoire,  1788-9  (not  seen)  ;  M. 
Cantor,  op.  tit.,  vol.  iv,  1908,  pp.  174  (article  by  F.  Cajori),  227  (article  by 
E.  Netto). 

143  Ibid.,  pp.  331-355- 

144  Ibid.,  pp.  344,  346. 
"5  Ibid.,  p.  347- 

146  "Reflexions  sur  le  Principe  de  la  moindre  Action  de  M.  de  Maupertuis," 
Hist,  de  I'Acad.  Roy.  des  Sci.,  1749  (Paris,  1753),  Memoires,  pp.  531-538. 
There  is  an  account  of  this  memoir  in  the  Histoire,  pp.  179-181.  Patrick 
d'Arcy  was  born  on  Sept.  18  (27),  1725,  at  Galloway  and  died  on  Oct.  18, 
1779.  ^  He  was  a  count,  a  field  marshal  of  France,  and  a  "Pensionnaire-Geo- 
metre"  of  the  Paris  Academy  (Poggendorffs  biog.-lit.  Handwortcrbuch,  vol. 
i>  P-  57)-  Cf.  M.  Cantor,  op.  cit.,  vol.  iv,  1908,  p.  18  (article  by  S.  Giinther). 

™Ibid.t  pp.  535-536. 


446  THE  MONIST. 

a  body  around  a  point  to  be  the  product  m.v.p,  where  p  is  the  per- 
pendicular drawn  from  this  point  on  the  direction  of  the  body,  then 
the  total  action  existing  in  nature  at  any  instant  around  a  given 
point,  being  produced  in  one  given  body,  the  quantity  of  action  of  this 
body  will  always  be  the  same  around  this  point,1*8  and  from  this 
theorem  are  easily  deduced  the  principle  of  the  conservation  of  vis 
viva,  the  case  of  rest,  the  centers  of  oscillation  or  of  percussion,  the 
law  of  the  refraction  of  light,  and  so  on. 

With  regard  to  (1),  d'Arcy1^  gave  the  following  considera- 
tions. "If  two  bodies  produce  equilibrium,  that  is  to  say,  if  rest  fol- 
lows from  their  direct  impact,  without  our  knowing  to  what  the 
action  is  proportional,  it  (the  action)  must  necessarily  be  equal  in 
the  two  bodies ;  for  if  not,  then  it  would  follow  that  an  action  was 
in  equilibrium  with  a  lesser  action,  that  is  to  say  that  different  actions 
produce  the  same  effect.  Now,  can  we  imagine  that  two  equal  and 
similar  effects  can  be  produced  by  unequal  quantities  of  causes? 
This  does  not  imply  that  the  effect  is  proportional  to  its  cause,  but 
only  that  the  same  effect  is  always  produced  by  the  same  quantity 
of  cause  and  vice  versa. 

"Let  there  be  two  hard  bodies  A  and  B  perfectly  equal  and  pro- 
ceeding in  opposite  directions  with  equal  velocities,  then  clearly  rest 
will  follow  their  impact.  If  A,  proceeding  in  the  same  direction 
with  the  same  velocity,  is  impinged  upon  by  the  body  C  of  different 
mass  and  velocity,  but  such  that  rest  follows  impact,  I  believe  that 
nobody  can  deny  that  the  action  of  B  is  equal  to  that  of  C,  since  both 
destroy  the  velocity  of  A.  Can  we  have  another  idea  of  the  equality 
of  two  quantities  than  of  our  being  able  to  substitute  one  for  the 
other  without  changing  anything?"  If  B  proceeds  with  double  the 
velocity  of,  and  traverses  double  the  space  traversed  by,  C,  the  prin- 
ciple of  Maupertuis  says  that  the  mass  of  C  is  four  times  that  of  B ; 
and  this  is  contrary  to  what  we  find  by  the  laws  of  motion.  "Thus," 
concludes  d'Arcy,  "the  action  is  not  proportional  to  the  mass  multi- 
plied by  the  velocity  and  by  the  space  described." 

With  respect  to  (2),  d'Arcy150  remarked  that  if  two  bodies  A 
and  B  proceed  in  the  same  direction  with  the  velocities  a  and  b, 

148  This  theorem  was  given  by  d'Arcy  in  the   Paris  Memoires  for  1747 
(published  in  1752;  pp.  348-356)  under  the  title:  "Principe  general  de  Dyna- 
mique,  qui  donne  la  relation  entre  les  espaces  parcourus  et  les  temps,  quelque 
soit  le  systeme  de  corps  que  Ton  considere,  et  quelles  que  soient  leurs  actions 
les  uns  sur  les  autres."    This  memoir  (read  in  1746)  is  part  of  the  paper  (of 
three  memoirs)   entitled:  "Probleme  de  Dynamique"  on  pp.  344-361. 

149  Loc.  cit.,  pp.  532-533. 

150  Ibid.,  pp.  533-534- 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  447 

the  action  of  the  bodies  A  and  B  will  be  Aa2  +  B&2.  If  after  im- 
pact they  proceed  with  the  velocities  x  and  z,  their  action  after 
impact  will  be  A.r2  +  Bs2.  isi  Now  the  quantity  of  action  after  impact 
will  be  either  equal  to  or  less  than  or  greater  than  what  it  was  before 
impact:  if  it  is  equal  we  have  the  theorem  of  vis  viva,  which  does 
not  hold  for  hard  bodies  ;  if  it  is  greater  it  will  have  increased  by 
the  quantity 


if  it  is  smaller  it  will  be  diminished  by  the  quantity 


and  this  quantity  is  the  real  quantity  of  action  lost,  and  consequently 
is  that  employed  by  nature  to  produce  the  actual  change;  therefore 


or,  if  we  suppose  dx-dz, 

which  is  absurd.  It  is  not,  then,  the  destroyed  part  of  this  quantity 
which  is  a  minimum.  Maupertuis's  argument  is:  Suppose  that  the 
bodies  A  and  B  proceed  in  the  same  direction  with  the  velocities 
a  and  b  and  that  the  plane  on  which  they  are  moves  with  the  velocity 
x;  evidently  A  will  move  on  this  plane  with  a  velocity  a-x  and  B 
will  move  behind  with  a  velocity  x  —  b,  x  being  greater  than  b  and 
less  than  a.  Maupertuis  finds  that 

A(a-*)2  +  BO-£)2 
will  be  a  minimum  when  the  velocity  x  is  such  that 

A(a-*)=B(*-&), 

that  is  to  say,  when  the  bodies  are  in  equilibrium  on  this  plane. 
"I  vow,"  said  d'Arcy,J53  "that  I  do  not  know  what  consequence  one 
can  deduce  from  this  other  than:  AP2+BQ2  being  a  minimum  and 
P2  =  CQ.dx  and  Q2=  fA.of.r,  we  will  have 


and  consequently  if 

A.Z  =  B.X, 

where  Z  and  X  are  functions  of  x,  then  AZ2  +  BX2  will  always  be  a 
minimum,  and  vice  versa;  and  this  leads  me  to  believe  that,  when 
one  has  found  that  A.Z2  +  B.X2  is  a  minimum,  one  knew  that 
A.Z  =  B.X." 

1  "Since  a,  b,  x  and  z  express  the  spaces  as  well  as  the  velocities." 
152  For  hard  bodies  x  =.  z  and  for  elastic  ones  a  —  b  =  z  —  x. 
163  Ibid.,  p.  534- 


448  THE  MONIST. 

With  regard  to  (3),  when  Maupertuis  deduced  the  law  of  the 
lever  from  his  principle  of  least  action,  he  made  a  gratuitous  sup- 
position, that  the  lever  moves  with  a  constant  angular  velocity.15* 
To  find  the  point  of  the  lever  (of  length  C)  about  which  two  bodies 
of  masses  A  and  B  at  the  ends  of  the  lever  produce  equilibrium, 
Maupertuis  called  Z  the  distance  of  A  to  the  sought  point,  and  an- 
nounced that,  to  solve  the  problem,  he  would  suppose  the  lever  to 
receive  some  small  movement  and  then  express  that  the  quantity  of 
action  is  the  smallest  possible.  If,  remarked  d'Arcy,  we  call  V  the 
small  velocity  of  A  and  suppose  that  A  describes  a  space  a,  the 
velocity  of  B  and  the  space  described  by  it  will  be,  respectively, 

V(C-Z)/Z  and  o(C-Z)/Z, 
and  the  action  of  the  bodies  will  be 

AVo   +   BVa(C-Z)2/Z, 

and  the  differential  equated  to  zero,  supposing  that  a  and  V  are 
constant,  gives  Z-C.  Maupertuis  gets  the  correct  law  by  suppos- 
ing that  the  lever  moves  with  a  constant  angular  velocity.  But  this 
supposition,  says  d'Arcy,  "seems  to  me  absolutely  gratuitous,  since, 
to  each  value  of  Z,  the  action  or  the  time  necessary  for  it  to  describe 
the  constant  angle  is  different." 

With  regard  to  (5),  d'Arcy155  remarks  that  his  definition  of 
action  is  in  perfect  agreement  with  d'Alembert's:156  "The  action  is 
the  movement  that  a  body  produces  or  tends  to  produce  in  another 
body." 

D'Arcy 's  principle  is  that  the  sum  of  the  masses  of  a  system, 
each  mass  being  multiplied  by  the  sector  which  it  describes  around 
a  fixed  point  in  the  same  time,  less  the  sum  of  the  sectors  described 
in  the  contrary  sense,  each  being  multiplied  by  the  mass  of  the 
body  which  describes  it,  is  proportional  to  the  time.  The  only  dif- 
ference from  the  principle  that  d'Arcy  gave  in  this  memoir  of  1749 
is  that  instead  of  (as  in  1747)  sectors  multiplied  by  masses,  were 
used  in  1749  the  equivalent  expressions  m.v.p. 

Let  two  bodies  A  and  B  move  with  the  velocities  a  and  b  before 
impact  and  with  the  velocities  x  and  s  after  impact.  By  the  above 
principle  the  action  of  A  and  B  round  any  point  O  will  be  the  same 
after  as  before  the  impact ;  thus,  where  P  is  the  foot  of  the  perpen- 
dicular from  O  on  the  line  joining  A  and  B, 

™  Ibid.,  p.  535- 
mlbid.tp.  536. 
158  In  the  Encyclopedic  (not  seen). 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  449 


and  consequently 

A(a-*)=B(*-&), 

and  this  relation  between  the  velocity  lost  by  A  and  that  gained  by 
B  holds  whether  the  bodies  are  elastic  or  not.  In  elastic  bodies  we 
easily  see  that  a-b-z-x,  and  hence,  from  the  above  equation 


which  is  the  property  of  vires  vivae.157 

If  two  bodies  A  and  B  strike  the  ends  P  and  Q  of  a  straight 
lever  with  the  same  velocity  a,  to  find  the  fulcrum-point  C  of  the 
bar  such  that  A  and  B  remain  at  rest  after  the  impact,  d'Arcy158  ob- 
serves that  the  action  of  A  round  C  must  be  equal  to  the  action  of 
B  round  C,  and  thus  C  is  the  Center  of  gravity.  By  the  same 
method  we  find  the  centers  of  oscillation  or  of  percussion,  and  so  on. 

When  deducing  the  law  of  the  refraction  of  light, I™  d'Arcy  ob- 
serves that,  in  his  memoir  of  1747,  he  had  proved  that  it  is  the  same 
thing  whether  the  bodies  are  attracted  toward  the  point  round  which 
the  action  is  sought  or  not,  as  the  quantity  of  this  action  is  not  altered 
thereby.  Let  FG  be  the  surface  of  a  diaphanous  and  homogeneous 
sphere  of  center  C,  M  a  point  outside  the  sphere,  and  N  a  point  in- 
side. A  ray  of  light — /A  being  the  mass  of  a  corpuscle  of  light — 
travels  from  M  to  N,  its  velocity  outside  the  sphere  being  v  and 
inside  the  sphere  being  u,  meeting  the  surface  at  m.  "The  action 
of  the  surface  FG  can  only  be  towards  the  center  C;  for  whatever 
action  this  body  may  have  on  the  corpuscle  of  light  on  one  side  of 
the  perpendicular  to  the  surface,  it  will  have  the  same  action  on  the 
other  side."  Thus  we  have 

fjL.v.CR  =  fjL.u.Cr, 

and  this  gives  the  known  law  of  refraction  of  light.  The  case  of 
FG  being  plane  instead  of  spherical  is  then  treated,  and  d'Arcy 
finally  remarks  that  other  examples  of  the  application  of  his  prin- 
ciples are  given  in  the  memoir  of  1747. 

XVI. 

The  Berlin  Histoire  for  1752,  published  in  1754,  contains  among 
the  memoirs  of  the  class  of  Speculative  Philosophy  a  "Reponse  a  un 
Memoire  de  M.  d'Arcy  insere  dans  le  Volume  de  1'Academie  Royale 

167  D'Arcy,  loc.  cit.,  p.  537. 

158  Ibid. 

™Ibid.,  pp.  537-538. 


45O        .  THE  MONIST. 

des  Sciences  de  Paris  pour  1'annee  1749"  by  Maupertuis,l6°  which 
is  headed  by  a  notice,161  in  italics,  stating  that  the  memoir  (1744) 
in  which  the  principle  of  the  least  quantity  of  action  was  first  com- 
municated was  received  by  the  Paris  Academy,  Maupertuis  "dares 
to  say,  with  some  applause  (applaudissment)."  Then  Maupertuis 
refers  to  his  paper  of  1746,  to  his  Essai  de  Cosmologie,  to  the  attacks 
of  "un  Professeur  de  la  Haye"  to  whom,  as  he  used  libels,  he  will 
never  reply,  and  to  d'Arcy  who  "attacks  with  so  much  politeness  and 
modesty,"  that  Maupertuis  thinks  that  he  ought  to  reply  to  him.  He 
appears,  says  Maupertuis,  "to  be  such  a  lover  of  the  truth  that  I  will 
try  to  introduce  him  to  it."162 

(1)  D'Arcy  tried  to  show  that  Maupertuis  is  wrong  to  call 
m.v.s  action.     Maupertuis  believed  that  he  had  good  grounds  for 
justifying  the  name;  but,  to  cut  matters  short,  Maupertuis  said  that 
he   had   adopted   Leibniz's   definition. l6^     D'Arcy 's    reason   against 
calling  the  above  product  action  reduces  to  this:  In  the  impact  of 
hard  bodies,  two  different  quantities  of  action  reduce  to  rest  one 
and  the  same  body  moving  with  the  same  velocity.    By  the  same  kind 
of  reasoning,  says  Maupertuis,  d'Arcy  might  object  to  the  name  vis 
viva-,  for  two  different  vires  vivae  can  reduce  the  same  hard  body 
to  rest."    And  in  fact  here  the  vis  viva  is  the  same  as  the  action, 
for  here  "the  space  is  proportional  to  the  velocity. "l6*    Again,  with 
elastic  bodies,  if  two  unequal  bodies  with  the  same  vires  mortuae 
(m.v)  strike  a  third  body  at  rest,  different  vires  mortuae  will  come 
into  existence  or  perish. 

(2)  D'Arcy,  to  show  that  Maupertuis  is  wrong  in  holding  that 
the  quantity  of  action  necessary  to  produce  any  change  in  nature 
is  a  minimum,  confuses,  when  treating  of  impact,  change  of  the 
quantity  of  action  with  change  of  velocities. l6s    The  velocities  can 
change  without  the  quantity  of  action  changing,  as  is  the  case  in  the 
impact  of  elastic  bodies  (when  this  quantity  is  the  same  as  the  quan- 

™Histoire  de  I'Acad.  de  Berlin,  1752,  T.  VIII,  pp.  293-298. 

161  Ibid.,  pp.  293-294. 

162 "....et  paroit  si  Amateur  de  la  verite,  que  je  tacherai  de  la  lui  faire 
connoitre"  {ibid.,  p.  294). 

103 ". ..  .mais  pour  trancher  court  avec  M.  d'Arcy,  je  puis  dire  que  ce  n'est 
pas  mon  affaire.  Leibnitz,  et  ceux  qui  1'ont  suivi,  ont  appele  ainsi  le  produit 
du  corps  par  1'espace  et  par  la  vitesse;  j'ai  adopte  une  definition  etablie,  contre 
laquelle  on  n'avoit  point  dispute,  et  que  je  n'avois  aucune  raison  de  changer; 
voila  ce  qu'il  me  suffiroit  de  repondre" ;  ibid.,  p.  295.  Apparently  this  is  upon 
what  E.  du  Bois-Reymond  relies  when  he  says  {op.  cit.,  p.  48)  :  "Maupertuis 
borrowed,  as  he  himself  says,  the  concept  and  name  of  action  from  Leibniz. . ." 
.  295- 
.  296. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  451 

tity  of  vis  z'iva)  ;  in  the  impact  of  hard  bodies,  the  change  of  the 
velocities  is  neither  equal  nor  proportional  to  the  change  in  the  quan- 
tity of  action. 

jf  166  {-fog  bodies  are  elastic,  the  change  is :  A  which  moved  before 
with  the  velocity  a  moves  afterwards  with  the  velocity  a,  and  the 
corresponding  velocities  of  B  are  b  and  ft.  If  then  we  wish  that 
afterwards  A  should  move  with  the  velocity  a  and  B  with  the  veloc- 
ity b,  we  must  transport  the  A-plane  with  the  velocity  a- a  and  the 
B-plane  with  the  velocity  f$  —  b\  and  from  this  we  must  get  the  quan- 
tity of  action  A(a-a)2  +  B(/3-b)2  necessary  to  produce  the  change 
in  nature,  and  which  is  a  minimum.  If  A  and  B  are  hard,  and  the 
common  velocity  after  the  impact  is  x,  and  if  we  wish  each  body  to 
move  with  its  original  velocity,  we  proceed  as  before,  and  get,  for 
the  quantity  of  action  necessary  to  produce  this  change,  A  (a  —  ,r)2  + 
B(,r-fr)2,  the  smallest  possible. 

(3)  D'Arcy's  criticism  on  Maupertuis's  deduction  of  the  lever 
is  mistaken,  for  Maupertuis  supposed  the  lever  to  be  in  a  state  of 
rest  and  infinitely  little  displaced  from  this  state.167 

Finally,  Maupertuis168  mentioned  the  incompleteness  of  this 
theory  of  the  lever,  which  was  not  remarked  by  d'Arcy,  but  about 
which  we  have  read  in  connection  with  the  reprint  of  the  memoir 
of  1740169  in  Maupertuis's  GLuvres.1"?0 

XVII. 

In  the  Paris  Memoires  for  1752  appeared  a  reply  by  d'Arcy171 
to  Maupertuis's  paper  in  the  Berlin  Memoir es  for  1752.  After  a 
few  preliminary  words  in  which  what  looks  like  sarcasm  is  veiled  in 
words  of  compliment — Maupertuis's  "modesty,"  "politeness,"  and 
"simplicity"  being  praised,  d'Arcy172  confesses  that  if  he  had  need 
of  a  proof  of  an  arranging  intelligence  he  would  find  it  just  as  much 
in  the  uniformity  of  the  laws  of  generation  of  the  vilest  insects  as 
in  the  general  laws  of  mechanics. 

166  Ibid.,  pp.  296-297. 

167  Ibid.,  pp.  297-298. 

168  Ibid.,  p.  298. 

169  Mapertuis  here  refers  to  this  paper  as  being  in  the  Memoires  for  1743. 
This  is,  of  course,  a  misprint. 

170  See  section  II  above. 

1  "Replique  a  un  Memoire  de  M.  de  Maupertuis,  sur  le  principe  de  la 
moindre  action,  insere  dans  les  Memoires  de  1' Academic  royale  des  Sciences 
de  ^Berlin,  de  1'annee  1752,"  Hist,  de  I'Acad.  Roy.  des  Set.,  1752  (Paris,  1756), 
Memoires,  pp.  503-519. 
172 1 bid.,  p.  503. 


452  THE  MONIST. 

With  regard  to  Maupertuis's  (correct)  classification  of  d'Arcy's 
objections  under  three  heads,  d'Arcy'73  maintains  that  the  first  still 
holds,  for  "when  someone  says  that  nature  economizes  action,  he 
clearly  means  that  this  quantity  expresses  this  cause  or  the  real 
force,"  and  d'Arcy'74  even  accuses  Maupertuis  of  falling  back  on 
the  authority  of  Leibniz.  His  argument  depends  for  its  validity 
on  the  principle  that  a  definition  is  something  more  than  the  mere 
giving  of  a  name. 

With  regard  to  d'Arcy's  second  objection,  d'Arcy^s  quoted 
from  the  Encyclopedic1"?6  to  show  that  Maupertuis's  phrase  "change 
happened  in  nature"  and  that  his  own  interpretation  of  this  phrase 
in  the  above  simple  case  of  impact  as 


which  is  to  be  a  minimum,  so  that 


is  natural  and  also  showed1  77  that  Maupertuis  himself  implied  this 
interpretation. 

Then  d'Arcy^8  showed  that  the  manner  in  which  Maupertuis 
used  his  principle  in  the  case  of  the  refraction  of  light  is  different 
from  that  in  which  he  used  it  in  the  case  of  impact.  If  we  treated 
the  latter  case  like  the  former,  we  should  have  the  result  that 


is  a  minimum,  and  hence  that 

Aa2  +  B/?2  =  0. 

In  the  case  of  light,  it  is  the  action  before  the  change  plus  the 
action  after  the  change  which  is  a  minimum  ;  in  impact  it  is  the  mass 
by  the  velocity  lost  and  by  the  space  which  will  be  described  in  conse- 
quence of  this  velocity. 

With  respect  to  Maupertuis's  reply  to  d'Arcy's  third  objection, 
Maupertuis,  says  d'Arcy,I79  has  misread  the  objection:  there  was  not 
said  to  be  a  supposition  about  an  angular  and  constant  motion  but 
about  a  constant  angular  motion.  D'Arcy  quotes  objections  nearly 
the  same  as  his  of  1749  from  the  above  cited  article  on  "Cosmo- 


173  Ibid.,  p.  504 
™Ibid.,  p.  506. 


™Ibid.,  pp.  507-508. 

178  Article  "Cosmologie,"  p.  196  [not  seen]. 

177  D'Arcy,  loc.  tit.,  pp.  508-509. 


178  Loc.  cit.,  pp.  509-510. 
178  Ibid.,  pp.  510-511. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  453 

logic" :  "When  Maupertuis  applies  his  principle  to  the  case  of  equi- 
librium in  the  lever,  certain  suppositions  must  be  made,  amongst 
others,  that  the  velocity  is  proportional  to  the  distance  from  the  ful- 
crum,180 and  that  the  time  is  constant  as  in  the  case  of  impact.  ..." 

In  the  case  of  the  reflection  of  light,  d'Arcy181  shows  that  nature 
is  prodigal  or  avaricious  of  action  as  a  mirror  is  more  or  less  concave 
respectively,  and  again  quoted  the  article  "Cosmologie"  on  this 
point. 

Finally,  d'Arcy182  returned  to  his  principle  of  1747,  which  he 
prepared  to  substitute  for  Maupertuis's  principle.  l8s 

XVIII. 

In  the  Berlin  Histoire  for  1753,  published  in  1755,  the  only 
paperl84  relating  to  the  principle  of  least  action  is  an  "Examen  des 
Reflexions  de  M.  le  Chevalier  d'Arcy  sur  le  Principe  de  la  moindre 
action"  by  Louis  Bertrand. lgs  Bertrand's  paper  was  headed  by  a 
note  to  the  effect  that,  as  the  Paris  Academy  of  Sciences  had,  con- 
trary to  its  custom,  hurried  to  publish  in  its  Memoir cs  of  1749  some 
reflexions  of  d'Arcy  which  he  had  only  given  in  1752,  the  Berlin 
Academy  believed  that  it  might  publish  this  examination  one  year 
before  it  ought  to  have  appeared. 

D'Arcy,  says  Bertrand,186  undertook  to  overthrow  Maupertuis's 
principle,  but  only  succeeded  in  overthrowing  the  false  ideas  which 
he  had  formed  about  it.  In  the  first  place,  d'Arcy  objected  to  Mau- 

180  As  d'Arcy  expressed  it,  that  the  angular  velocity  is  constant. 

181  Ibid.,  pp.  511-513. 

182  Ibid.,  pp.  513-519.    On  p.  513  he  emphasized  that  the  memoir  containing 
this  principle  was  read  to  the  French  Academy  in  1746. 

183  On  d'Arcy's  memoirs  see  Mayer,  op.  cit.,  pp.  13-15,  21.    It  seems  to  me 
that  Mayer's  view  of  these  memoirs  is  too  favorable.     I  will  return  to  this 
point  in  my  criticisms. 

184  The  contrary  was  stated,  owing  to  a  wrong  reading  of  A.  Mayer,  op. 
cit.,  p.   17,  by  myself  in  Ostwalds  Klassiker,  No.   167,  p.  36;  but,  of  Euler's 
five  papers  in  this  volume,  one  is  on  Daniel  Bernoulli's  papers  on  vibrating 
cords  (cf.  M.  Cantor,  op.  cit.,  vol.  iii,  ad  ed.,  Leipsic,  1901,  pp.  904-907),  two 
papers    are    on    spherical    and    spheroidical    trigonometry    deduced    from   the 
method  of  maxima  and  minima   (cf.  ibid.,  pp.  867-869),  one  on  the  law  of 
refraction  of  rays  of  different  colors,  and  one  on  the  paths  of  projectiles  in 
resisting  media ; — and  in  none  of  these  is  any  reference  to  the  principle  of  least 
action  except  in  a  passage   (p.  306)   in  the  last  line  but  one  of  these  papers, 
where  he  refers  to  the  convincing  proof  of  the  existence  of  a  Deity  given  by 
Maupertuis,  and  also  to  the  argument  from  the  wonderful  structure  of  the 
eye. 

185  Pp.  310-320.     Louis  Bertrand  (1731-1812)  was  then  in  Berlin  and  was 
a  friend  of  Euler's ;  cf.  Poggendorff,  vol.  i,  p.  171 ;  M.  Cantor,  op.  cit.,  vol.  iv, 
Leipsic,  1908,  p.  332  (article  by  V.  Bobynin). 

188  Op.  cit.,  p.  311. 


454  THE  M  ON  IST. 

pertuis's  definition  of  action.  This  is  a  question  of  words  ;l8?  d'Arcy 
required  that  the  action  of  different  hard  bodies  should  be  estimated 
equal  if  each  of  these  bodies  is  capable  of  reducing  to  rest  the  same 
hard  body  endowed  with  a  certain  velocity,  so  that  the  action  of  a 
body  is  measured  by  m.v.  But,  says  Bertrand,  it  is  well  known188 
that,  in  the  impact  of  hard  bodies,  a  part  of  the  motion  is  destroyed 
— that  part  which  would  be  reproduced  if  the  bodies  were  elastic: 
"hence  it  follows  that,  if  a  hard  body  (A)  of  mass  1  and  velocity 
1  were  reduced  to  rest  both  by  a  body  (B)  of  mass  1  and  velocity  1 
and  by  a  body  (C)  of  mass  %  and  velocity  2,  we  could  only  affirm 
positively  that  the  action  of  B  is  equal  to  that  of  C  if  we  have  pre- 
viously proved  that  when  B  impinges  on  A  it  loses  the  same  quan- 
tity of  motion  as  when  C  impinges  on  A.  For  if  it  were  true  that  in 
one  case  more  motion  were  lost  than  in  the  other,  the  rest  in  this  case 
ought  not  to  be  attributed  to  the  equality  of  action  of  the  two  bodies, 
but  to  the  greater  loss  of  motion ;  in  fact,  if  this  loss  had  not  been 
greater,  some  motion  would  have  been  left  for  the  bodies  which  have 
impinged,  and  thus  rest  would  not  have  followed  the  impact. 

"In  order,  then,  that  the  reasoning  by  which  M.  d'Arcy  has 
wished  to  prop  up  his  definition  of  action  should  be  conclusive,  it 
would  be  necessary  for  him  to  prove  that  the  same  quantity  of  mo- 
tion is  lost  whether  B  impinges  on  A  or  C  impinges  on  A.  Now 
this  he  will  never  prove. 

"Not  being  able  to  do  anything  in  that  direction,  perhaps  he 
will  claim  that  it  is  sufficient  to  attend  to  the  change  which  happens 
to  the  body  A  after  the  impact ;  but,  if  <he  only  pays  regard  to  the 
effect  produced  on  the  body  impinged  upon,  we  can  urge  against 
him  the  impact  of  elastic  bodies,  where  a  body  A  of  mass  and  veloc- 
ity both  1  is  reduced  to  rest  both  by  a  body  B  of  mass  1  and  velocity 
0,  by  a  body  C  whose  velocity  and  mass  are  both  %,  and  by  a  body 
D  whose  mass  is  %  and  velocity  1.  Now,  M.  d'Arcy  would  con- 
tradict his  own  definition  of  action  if  he  claimed  that  the  actions 
of  B,  C,  and  D  were  all  equal  to  one  another.  Thus  the  foundation 
on  which  M.  d'Arcy  wished  to  support  his  manner  of  estimating 
action  absolutely  lacks  solidity."  In  d'Arcy's  last  paragraph  on  the 
definition  of  action,  he  wrongly  concludes,  says  Bertrand,18?,  that 
from  Maupertuis's  definition  of  action,  follows  that  whenever  the 

™Ibid.,  pp.  311-312,  313- 

188 " Cest  une  chose  dont  tons  les  Philosophies  conviennent "  (ibid., 

p.  312). 

189  Ibid.,  pp.  313-314- 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  455 

velocities  and  the  masses  of  two  hard  bodies  are  such  that  rest  follows 
the  impact  of  these  bodies,  the  actions  of  these  bodies  are  equal. 

With  regard  to  d'Arcy's  attack  on  Maupertuis's  principle,  Ber- 
trand190 remarks  that  Maupertuis  expressly  said  that  not  the  differ- 
ence of  the  actions  before  and  after  the  impact,  but  the  quantity  of 
action  necessary  to  produce  this  change  is  to  be  a  minimum.  The 
quantity  of  action  necessary  to  produce  a  change  is  not  the  difference 
of  the  actions  before  and  after  the  change  ;  but  it  is  the  product  of 
the  mass  of  the  bodies  whose  state  is  changed,  the  space  that  these 
bodies  describe  in  consequence  of  (en  suite  du)  the  change,  and  the 
velocity  with  which  they  describe  it,  also  in  consequence  of  the 
change.191 

With  regard  to  d'Arcy's  strictures  on  Maupertuis's  treatment 
of  the  lever,  Bertrand192  reproduces  d'Arcy's  supposition  that  A 
moves  with  a  small  velocity  V  and  describes  a  space  a,  whence  the 
velocity  of  B  is  V(c  —  z)/z,  the  space  described  by  B  is  a(c  —  s)/z, 
and  the  action  of  the  whole  system  is 


Then,  before  differentiating,  d'Arcy  supposed  V  and  a  constant  ;  and 
Bertrand  inquires  why  should  the  velocity  of  and  space  described 
by  A  be  supposed  to  be  constant  rather  than  those  of  and  by  B. 
Maupertuis  puts  as  constant  the  angle  that  A  and  B  describe  around 
the  fulcrum  of  the  lever  ;  and  this  supposition  does  not  affect  one 
of  the  bodies  rather  than  the  other,  for  this  angle  is  the  same  for 
both  bodies.  Still,  this  supposition  appears  gratuitous  to  d'Arcy 
because  for  each  value  of  z  the  action  or  the  time  necessary  to  make 
A  and  B  describe  the  angle  supposed  constant  is  different.  But, 
says  Bertrand,  if  the  action  necessary  to  make  A  and  B  describe  the 
angle  supposed  constant  were  not  different  for  each  value  of  z,  it 
would  be  absurd  to  seek  which  of  these  actions  is  the  least. 

With  regard  to  d'Arcy's  assertion  that,  whatever  the  laws  of 
nature  might  be,  it  would  always  be  easy  to  find  a  function  of  the 
velocities  and  masses  such  that,  when  minimized,  it  would  give  these 
laws,  Bertrand19^  remarks  that  "that  may  be  true  of  many  particular 
cases."  Rather  earlier  in  his  paper,  Bertrand19*  remarks  a  propos 

100  Ibid.,  p.  314- 
1M/Wd.,  pp.  314-315- 
102  Ibid.,  pp.  317-318. 
**Ibid.  p.  318. 
194  7Md.,  pp.  315-316. 


456  THE  MONIST. 

of  d'Arcy's  suggestion  that  Maupertuis  knew  the  formula  A(a-^r)  = 
B(JT  —  b)  for  impact  and  concluded  that  the  action  must  be 

A(a-.*-)2  +  BO-&)2 

in  order  that  the  known  formula  should  result  when  the  action  was 
minimized,  and  d'Arcy's  attempted  generalization,  that,  if  Z  and  X 
are  functions  of  x,  then,  if  AZ 


will  always  be  a  minimum  and  vice  versa,  that  this  generalization 
will  always  be  false  except  when  dZ  +  d*K  =  0,  —  the  case  which  he 
wished  to  generalize. 

The  rest  of  Bertrand's^s  paper  is  devoted  to  d'Arcy's  own 
principle.  "This  principle,"  says  Bertrand,196  "can  in  a  certain  sense 
be  admitted,  but  it  will  never  lead  to  important  discoveries  ;  still 
less  will  it  show  us,  so  to  speak,  the  true  ends  in  view  of  nature: 
and  these  circumstances  put  it  infinitely  below  that  of  M.  de  Mau- 
pertuis." 

With  regard  to  the  way  in  which  Bertrand's  paper  is  written, 
it  seems  both  magisterial  and  hasty  :  attempts  at  sarcasm  against 
d'Arcy  and  flattery  —  or  perhaps  sincere  reverence  —  for  Maupertuis 
stand  out  too  prominently.  Bertrand  was  young  when  he  wrote  it, 
so  there  is  a  greater  chance  that  he  was  sincere.  Still,  he  was  of, 
or  was  about  to  be  of,  the  Berlin  Academy. 

XIX. 

We  will  now  give  a  brief  retrospect  of  the  development  of  views 
on  the  principle  of  least  action,  and  dispose  of  all  historical  questions 
before  trying  to  elicit  what  gains  have  resulted  for  knowledge  by  this 
development. 

A.  Mayer19?  says  of  Euler's  formulations  of  the  principle  of 
least  action:  "We  shall  see  that  this  correct  form  [in  the  second 
appendix  to  the  Methodus  of  1744]  got  lost  to  him  in  the  course  of 
time,  and  that  soon  it  lost  as  much  in  rigor  as  it  appeared  to  gain 
in  generality."  Mayer's198  grounds  for  this  view  were  that  Ja- 
cobi's199  principle  of  least  action  was  the  "true"  principle,  owing  to 

195  Ibid.,  pp.  318-320.  Just  at  the  end  is:  "On  pourroit  faire  encore  nom- 
bre  de  reflexions  stir  rinsuffisance  de  ce  Principe  applique  a  la  refraction  des 
rayons^  de  lumiere;  mais  il  semble  qu'il  y  auroit  une  sorte  de  mauvaise  hu- 
meur  a  examiner  si  rigoureusement  se  que  M.  d'Arcy  paroit  avoir  voulu 
trailer  cavalierement."  I  have  left  the  accents  unaltered. 


.  319- 

197  Op.  cit.,  p.  6. 

198  Op.  cit.,  pp.  6-1  1. 

199  Cf.  Monist,  vol.  xxii,  April,  1912. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  457 

the  difficulty  there  appeared  to  be200  if  the  time  was  not  eliminated, 
and  this  elimination  had  apparently  to  be  done  by  the  equation  ex- 
pressing the  conservation  of  vis  viva.  Thus  the  principle  of  least 
action  is  subject  to  the  limitations  implied  by  the  subsistence  of 
the  theorem  of  vis  viva.  Thus  Euler,  in  the  above  mentioned  appen- 
dix, expressly  pointed  out  that  his  theorem  cannot  hold  for  motion 
in  a  resisting  medium,  and  that,  in  the  integrand,  the  velocity  must 
be  expressed  "ex  viribus  sollicitantibus  per  quantitates  ad  curvam 
pertinentes.201  Consequently  Mayer202  maintained  that  Lagrange's 
(1760)  generalization  of  the  principle  of  least  action  is,  in  the  form 
in  which  Lagrange  states  it,  meaningless,  and  the  theorem  which 
he  really  had  in  his  mind  is  that  known  as  "Hamilton's  principle" 
given  by  Hamilton  in  1835.  We  know203  that  later  on  (in  a  publi- 
cation of  1886)  Mayer  changed  this  view,  owing  to  acquaintance 
with  a  paper  of  Rodrigues's  (1816)  in  which  the  time  (the  t  in  the 
integrand)  was  varied  by  the  8-process  of  the  calculus  of  variations, 
and  admitted  that  there  are  two  forms  of  the  principle  of  least  ac- 
tion :  Jacobi's  and  Lagrange's.  This  view  has  been  confirmed  by 
the  later  researches  of  H61der.2°4 

Now  Jacobi's  principle  may  be  considered  to  be  a  generalized 
form  of  Euler's  theorem,  and  Lagrange's  principle  a  more  precise 
and  generalized  form  of  Maupertuis's.  So  it  happens  that  Mau- 
pertuis  was  right  in  thinking  his  theorem  quite  general,  and  Euler 

200  Ibid. 

^Methodus,  p.  312.  Cf.  pp.  318-319  on  the  necessity  for  the  principle  of 
vis  viva. 

202  Op.  cit.,  pp.  26-29.  Mayer  (ibid.,  p.  24)  also  remarked  that  Euler's 
later  (Maupertuisian)  form  of  the  principle,  in  which  the  condition  that  all  the 
quantities  in  the  integrand  must  be  reduced,  by  means  of  the  principle  of  vis 
viva,  to  space-elements  alone  is  not  stated,  is  quite  meaningless,  for  the  forces 
acting  on  the  system,  on  which  the  path  of  the  system  depends,  do  not  occur 
in  the  integral  of  action.  Here  we  will  anticipate  our  criticism  by  pointing 
out  that  in  Lagrange's  memoir  the  conditoin 

ST  =  5U, 

where  "T"  and  "SU"  have  the  meaning  already  explained  in  The  Monist,  vol. 
xxii,  April,  1912,  p.  290,  is  explicitly  given,  and  what  would  now  be  written 
in  the  same  way  was,  tacitly  or  not,  presupposed  in  all  Euler's  works. 
Mayer  said  that  the  problem  of  variations  only  subsisted  under  the  con- 
dition 

T  =  U  +  const., 

which  implies  the  preceding  equation,  but,  as  Lagrange  pointed  out,  is  not 
necessarily  implied  by  it.  And  it  is  the  preceding  equation  alone  that  we  re- 
quire to  rescue  the  principle  of  least  action  from  meaninglessness.  Mayer's 
remark  (ibid.,  p.  27)  that  Lagrange  completely  leaves  out  the  condition  is 
simply  an  error. 


203  Cf.  Monist,  vol.  xxii,  April,  1912. 

204  Ibid. 


458  THE  MONIST. 

was  right  in  doing  what  Mayer20 s  complains  of — in  dropping  the 
condition  about  the  theorem  of  vis  viva  holding.206  Of  course,  it 
may  have  been,  and  probably  was,  the  case  that  neither  Maupertuis 
nor  Euler  had  any  good  grounds  for  believing  that  they  were  right. 
Indeed,  one  is  forced,  against  one's  will,  to  the  opinion  that  Euler 
was  in  a  position  in  which,  as  Mayer20?  expresses  it,  "he  could  not 
with  propriety  retort  to  the  powerful  President  of  his  Academy." 

The  only  reason  why  it  is  necessary  to  inquire  closely  whether 
Euler  really  considered  Maupertuis's  principle  to  be  valid  seems  to 
me  mainly  to  be  the  provision  of  an  example  to  show  the  necessity 
of  an  additional  condition  when  we  wish  to  deduce  properties  of 
motion  from  the  equation  of  the  variation  of  the  integral  of  action 
to  zero.  There  is  also  the  possibility  of  our  being  given  yet  another 
example  of  the  greater  power  of  instinctive  beliefs  or  "metaphysics" 
over  the  good  man's  mind  than  the  love  of  scientific  truth.208  If 
we  should  have  to  conclude  that  Euler  deliberately  hid  the  truth  for 
the  personal  favor  of  Maupertuis,  this  conclusion  will  fill  us  with  the 
same  regret  and  loathing  that  we  feel  for  the  weakness  in  Galileo's 
character  and  the  disgraceful  exercise  of  the  church's  power  on  him, 
respectively. 

It  seems  to  me  true  that  Euler's  love  for  "metaphysics"  alone 
could  not  lead  him  to  forsake  scrupulous  honesty  in  his  search  for 
the  truth.  It  is  difficult,  but  very  possible,  to  acquit  Euler  of  the 
charge  of  veiled  sarcasm  against  Maupertuis's  principle.  In  a  paper, 
from  which  we  have  quoted  above,  in  the  Berlin  Memoires  for  1748, 
he  expresses  his  belief  that  we  are  still  very  far  from  being  able  to 
assign,  for  each  effect  which  nature  produces,  the  quantity  of 
action  which  is  the  smallest,  and  from  being  able  to  deduce  it  from 
the  first  principles  of  our  knowledge.  Indeed,  Euler  seems  to  have 
no  doubt  that  something  must  be  a  minimum,  but  he  also  thinks 
that  this  something  may  be  different —  or  at  least  seem  to  us,  with- 
out imperfect  knowledge,  different — in  different  cases.2°9  At  any 
rate  Euler  goes  carefully  through  single  statical  cases  and  deter- 
mines the  equivalent  in  terms  of  the  forces  of  "the  quantity  of 

205  Op.  cit.,  pp.  23-24.  Euler  did  not,  however,  explicitly  drop  this  condition. 

206  Euler  had  presupposed   in   1744  that  the   principle  of  vis  viva   held: 
Maupertuis  considered  his  principle  applies  to  cases — such  as  the  impact  of 
inelastic  bodies — where  the  principle  of  vis  viva  does  not  hold. 

*"Ibid.,  p.  17. 

208  On  Euler's  "metaphysical"  tendencies,  cf.  Mayer,  ibid.,  pp.  21-23. 

200  Cf.  the  remark  of  d'Arcy  that,  whatever  the  laws  of  nature  might  be 
one  could  always  find  a  function  of  the  masses  and  velocities  which,  when 
minimized,  would  represent  them  (cf.  section  XV). 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  459 

action"  in  each  case.  Nowadays,  we  would  say,210  of  course,  that 
this  inductive  procedure  was  far  more  "reasonable"  or  scientific 
than  Maupertuis's ;  but  we  must  remember  that  then  the  opinion 
was  far  more  generally  held  than  it  is  now  that  knowledge  of 
the  truth  could  be  attained  by  other  than  scientific  methods. 

It  was,  I  think  we  must  say,  not  merely  love  for  "metaphysics" 
which  led  Euler  to  sacrifice  important  details  of  his  principle.  Com- 
parison of  Daniel  Bernoulli's  letter  to  Euler  of  September  4,  1743, 
with  Euler's  markedly  different  account  in  the  Berlin  Memoires  of 
1750  of  the  circumstances  about  the  publication  of  the  Methodus 
of  1744,  as  well  as  Euler's  obviously  unjust  attitude  towards  Konig, 
points  to  a  lower  influence.  If  we  dismissed — as  we  would  like — 
thoughts  that  this  sort  of  influence  came  in,  we  would  be  faced 
with  the  insoluble  problem  that  Euler  supported  a  principle  which 
was  claimed  to  embrace  cases  where  the  theorem  of  vis  viva  fails 
while  he  had  convinced  himself  that  the  subsistence  of  this  theorem 
was  a  necessary  condition  for  the  validity  of  the  principle.  And 
here  the  suggestion  arises  of  itself  that,  since  Euler,  in  his  papers 
in  the  Berlin  Memoires,  only  committed  himself  to  the  mathematical 
support — as  distinguished  from  warmly  expressed  admiration — of 
Maupertuis's  principle  in  statical  cases,  he  dared  not  affirm  that  the 
action-integral  was  a  minimum  in  nature  even  when  the  principle 
of  vis  viva  did  not  hold.211  This  stop  was  reserved  for  Lagrange, 
and  perhaps  it  was  on  this  account  that  Euler  in  a  letter  of  Novem- 
ber 9,  1762,  congratulated  Lagrange  in  the  words:212  "What  satis- 
faction would  M.  de  Maupertuis  not  have,  if  he  were  still  alive,  to 
see  his  Principle  of  least  action  carried  to  the  highest  degree  of 
dignity  of  which  it  is  susceptible.213  If  this  conjecture  be  true,  we 
must  believe  that  Euler  had  a  childlike  faith  that  "metaphysics" 
could  generalize  a  theorem  so  far  as  to  drop  a  condition  which  he 
had  satisfied  himself,  was  necessary.  We  know  now  that  this  faith 
— if  indeed  it  existed — was  justified. 

PHILIP  E.  B.  JOURDAIN. 

THE  LODGE,  GIRTON,  CAMBRIDGE,  ENGLAND. 

210  Like  Mayer,  op.  cit.,  p.  23. 

211  Indeed,  where  he  refers  to  dynamical  cases   (in  the  Berlin  Histoirc  of 
1751)   he  explicitly  uses  the  principle  of  vis  viva.     Euler  nowhere  refers  to 
the  problem  of  the  impact  of  inelastic  bodies,  on  which  Maupertuis  and  others 
laid  such  stress. 

212  GELuvres  de  Lagrange,  vol.  xiv,  p.  201. 

213  "Quelle  satisfaction  n'aurait  pas  M.  de  Maupertuis,  s'il  etait  encore  en 
vie,  de  voir  son  principe  de  la  moindre  action  porte  au  plus  haut  degre  de 
dignite  dont  il  est  susceptible." 


460  THE  MONIST. 

THE  CAPTURE  HYPOTHESIS  OF  T.  J.  J.  SEE.1 

In  the  opinion  of  Mr.  See,2  the  planets  were  not  formed  from 
fragments  of  the  solar  nebula,  nor  did  the  moon  originate  from  a 
piece  of  that  of  the  earth.  He  believes  that  the  planets  had  a  cosmic 
origin  outside  of  the  solar  nebula  ;  that  they  are  foreign  bodies  cap- 
tured by  the  sun  while  passing  near  it  in  their  journey  ;  and  that  in 
the  same  way  the  moon  was  captured  by  the  earth  at  a  certain  remote 
time. 

How  was  this  phenomenon  accomplished?  Mr.  See  thinks  that 
the  sun  was  formerly  surrounded  by  a  vast  atmosphere  and  that  the 
capture  took  place  as  the  result  of  a  resistance  created  by  this  at- 
mosphere. 

Let  us  therefore  study  the  effect  of  the  resistance  of  the  medium 
on  the  motion  of  a  planet.  3  If  there  were  no  resistance  the  motion 
would  be  Keplerian,  the  orbit  would  be  an  ellipse  of  any  eccentricity 
whatever.  The  density  of  the  resisting  medium  being  by  hypothesis 
very  small,  this  orbit  would  vary  slowly.  We  shall  study  the  varia- 
tions of  this  orbit  by  the  method  of  the  variation  of  constants. 

First  let  us  recall  some  formulas  pertaining  to  the  elliptical 
motion  of  planets. 

Calling  the  radius  vector  r  and  the  true  anomaly  v,  the  equation 

of  the  orbit  is 

/.      i 

1-f-^COSZ/ 

e  denoting  the  eccentricity,  and 

(2)  p  =  a(l-<?) 

denoting  the  parameter  of  the  elliptical  orbit  whose  major  axis  is 

2a.    We  have  also  the  equation  of  the  areas 


the  constant  C  of  the  areas  having  the  value 


C= 

in  which  M  represents  the  mass  of  the  sun.     (We  disregard  the 

1  Translated  by  Lydia  G.  Robinson  from  the  author's  Lemons  sur  les  hypo- 
theses cosmogoniques,  Chaps.  VI  and  XIII.     Paris,  Hermann,  1911. 

2  T.  J.  J.  See,  Researches  on  the  Evolution  of  the  Stellar  Systems,  Vol.  II, 
"The  Capture  Theory  of  Cosmical  Evolution."    Lynn,  Mass.,  Nichols  &  Sons ; 
Paris,  Hermann,  1910. 

3  See  he.  cit.t  Chap.  VII,  pp.  134-158. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  461 

mass  of  the  planet  compared  to  the  sun's  mass.)     The  mean  motion 
n  is  connected  with  half  the  major  axis  a  by  Kepler's  third  law. 
(3)  »V  =  M. 

Finally  the  equation  of  the  vis  viva  gives 

MM 

r~      2a 
in  which  T  is  half  the  vis  viva. 

Differentiating  equation   (1)   with  reference  to  time,  we  have 

dr         pe  sin  v      dv 
dt~  (I+ecos  v)2dt 

pe  sin  v      C 


pe  sin  v      C 

=  7i~7         —  \2^2 
(1+ecos  v)2P 

C 

=  —  •  esrnv. 
P 

Now  dr/dt  is  the  component  of  velocity  in  the  direction  of  the 
radius  vector.  The  component  perpendicular  to  this  radius  vector 
has  for  its  value 

dv     C 

r~dr~r 

Q 

=  —  (!+£  cos  v). 
P 

From  the  two  components  of  the  velocity  V,  we  derive  the  square 
of  this  velocity, 


In  short,  if  we  put 
we  shall  have 


The  above  formulas  belong  to  Keplerian  motion. 

Now  let  us  suppose  that  there  is  an  atmospheric  medium  with  a 
resistance  R  directly  opposed  to  the  velocity  and  function  of  the 


462  THE  MONIST. 

value  V  of  that  velocity.     The  constant  of  the  vires  vivae  -  M/2a 
during  the  time  dt  will  undergo  a  variation 

M  , 
Mda; 

this  variation  will  equal  the  work  of  the  resistance  R  which  is 
Hence  we  have 


p 

whence  we  derive 

da 2R/002 

dt"       A/M^' 

replacing  M  and  p  by  their  values  (2)  and  (3)  in  this  last  equation, 
we  obtain 

(4)  ^  = 

dt 

This  is  the  equation  which  gives  the  variation  of  the  major  axis ;  the 
second  member  is  necessarily  negative.  Hence  the  effect  of  the  resist- 
ance of  the  medium  is  always  to  diminish  a  and  consequently  according 
to  equation  (3)  to  increase  n.  The  angular  velocity  of  the  planet 
increases4  at  the  same  time  that  its  mean  distance  from  the  sun 
diminishes. 

W  shall  now  study  the  effect  of  resistance  of  the  medium  on  the 
eccentricity  of  the  orbit. 

First  of  all  the  derivative  dC/dt  of  the  areal  constant  C  would 
be  equal  to  the  momentum  of  the  disturbing  force  R,  with  reference 
to  the  center  of  attraction.    Now  this  force  R  opposed  to  the  veloc- 
ity has  for  its  components: 
in  the  direction  of  the  vector  ray 

dr 
dt 

-Rv' 

perpendicular  to  the  vector  ray 

4  Formula  (3)  even  shows  that  na  increases  as  a  diminishes,  whence  we 
have  the  curious  result  that  resistance  of  the  medium  causes  an  increase  in 
the  linear  velocity  of  the  planet. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  463 

dv 


and  the  momentum  of  the  force  R  with  reference  to  the  sun  is 

~dv 

R     *          RC- 

-~v":    "Rv 

Hence  we  have 

dC         RC 
~dt=    ""V~* 
Remember  that 

c= 


Taking  the  logarithmic  derivatives  of  the  two  extreme  members, 
we  have 


Col  i  ?  / 

2\a      1— <r/ 

This  equation  makes  it  possible  for  us  to  obtain  de  since  da  and  dC 
have  been  computed.    We  find 

2e     de     1  da _2  dC 
1 — F  dt     a  dt     C  dt ' 

an  equation  which  may  be  written  by  replacing  da/dt  and  dC/dt  by 
their  values   (4)   and   (5), 

2e    de  2Rp          2R 

^  '  T — ^"^=~ — r=r~'~"vr' 

Let  us  now  transform  the  second  member  of  this  equation.     We 
have  previously  found  (page  461) 

V  =  pJ^ 


na 


hence  the  second  member  may  assume  the  form 

_2.R_  r   i^i 

~na^^'      P    J' 

or  again,  by  restoring  the  value  of  p2,  this  other  form 

2R        2e  cos  v+2<? 


464  THE  MONIST. 

Finally  equation  (6)  then  gives 

/ 1—  \  CiC  £  JA.  A/  JL  —  €•*    /  \ 

(7)  3:=  — -(tf  +  coszO. 

dt  nap 

This  is  the  equation  which  gives  the  variation  of  the  eccentricity  of 
the  orbit. 

Formulas  (4)  and  (7)  make  it  possible  to  compute  at  any 
instant  the  variations  of  the  major  axis  and  of  the  eccentricity. 
But  here  it  is  only  desirable  to  obtain  their  secular  variations,  and  in 
order  to  do  this,  to  compute  the  value  of  da  and  de  during  the  time 
of  a  complete  revolution. 

Taking  as  an  independent  variable  the  true  anomaly  v  we  shall 
have 

da_da  dt^ 
dv~~ dt  dv 

de__de_  dt_ 
dv     dt  dv' 
Now  the  equation  of  the  areas 


(8) 


(9)  -- 

dv    C 

=P- 

Formulas  (4),  (7)  and  (9)  therefore  make  it  possible  to  write  the 
values  (8)  of  da/dv  and  de/dv  which,  integrated  between  0  and  2?r 
will  give  the  variations  of  half  the  major  axis  and  the  eccentricity 
during  one  revolution. 

We  may  here  offer  certain  hypotheses  on  medial  resistance  R. 
This  resistance  increases  as  the  velocity ;  we  shall  suppose  it  pro- 
portional to  a  certain  power  of  the  velocity  V.  It  varies  directly 
as  the  distance  r  from  the  sun,  for  the  density,  and  consequently  the 
resistance,  of  the  sun's  atmosphere  increases  inversely  as  the  dis- 
tance; let  us  suppose  R  proportional  to  a  certain  power  (negative) 
of  r.  In  short  let  us  put 

10)  R  =  AW-*f 

h,  a  and  ft  being  positive  constants.  Since  V  is  proportionate  to  p, 
and  r  to  l/(l+e  cosv),  we  can  write  formula  (10)  as  follows: 

R  =  £pa  (l+«?cos  v)*  , 

k  being  a  new  positive  constant. 

In  view  of  these  hypotheses  on  R,  the  values  (8)  of  da/dv  and 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  465 

de/dv,  computed  by  means  of  the  formulas  (4),  (7)  and  (9),  may 
be  written 


(11) 

dv 

where  H  denotes  the  positive  constant 


—  /~v> 

naC 
bear  in  mind  that  in  these  values  (11) 


In  order  to  study  the  secular  variations  of  a  and  e  we  must 
develop  the  second  members  of  the  values  (11)  in  trigonometric 
series  according  to  the  cosines  of  the  multiples  of  v,  and  integrate 
between  v  =  0  and  v  —  2?r.  By  integration  all  the  cosines  will  be  0  ; 
therefore  we  are  interested  in  the  constant  terms  of  these  trigono- 
metric developments  and  especially  the  sign  of  these  constant  terms. 

We  already  know  that  da/dv  is  necessarily  negative,  since  da/dt 
is  always  negative.  Therfore  we  shall  work  only  with  de/dv.  We 
must  develop  in  a  trigonometric  series  the  expression 

Pa~l(l+ecos  ^~2(^+cos  v). 

Now  if  we  first  develop  the  product  of  the  two  first  terms  we  ob- 
tain: 

(12)  pa-1(l+*cosz;)0-2  =  Ao+  Ai  cos  z>  +  A2  cos  2z;-f  ...  . 

We  observe  that  A0  is  necessarily  positive  because  it  is  the  mean 
value  of  the  first  member  both  of  whose  terms  are  always  positive. 
Then  multiplying  the  two  members  of  formula  (12)  by  (e  +  cosv) 
we  have 

Pa~1(l+e  cos  v)f*~2(e+cos  v)  =  (  Ao*+y  )  +...  , 

all  the  unwritten  terms  of  the  second  member  having  their  mean 
value  0. 

The  second  formula  (11)  therefore  gives  for  the  mean  value 
of  de/dv  during  one  revolution 

(13)  != 

Since  the  second  member  of  equation  (13)  is  generally  negative 
we  conclude  from  it  that  the  medial  resistance  has  the  effect  of 


466  THE  MONIST. 

diminishing  the  eccentricity  of  the  orbit.  This  would  be  the  case 
particularly  whenever  Ax  is  positive.  Now  according  to  formula  (12) 
we  have 


2  C* 
=  - 

TTj    o 


— 
2    (1+^cos  v)P~2cos  vdv. 


If  at  the  same  time 


Aj  will  be  positive,  for  of  two  elements  of  the  integral  correspond- 
ing to  the  two  values  v  and  ir-v  of  the  variable  of  integration,  one 
is  positive  and  the  other  negative,  but  the  positive  element  possesses 
a  greater  absolute  value  than  the  negative. 

In  an  analogous  way  we  know  that  if  the  two  inequalities 


are  satisfied,  we  shall  likewise  have 

Ai>0. 

If  we  suppose  the  eccentricity  e  to  be  so  small  that  we  can  dis- 
regard its  square  e~  we  shall  find  more  general  conditions.  The  second 
formula  (11)  is  reduced  to 

-/  =  -H [1+  (a-l)e  cos  z;+  (P-2)e  cos  v\  (<?+cos  v); 
dv 

whence  by  retaining  only  the  mean  value  of  the  second  member  we 
derive 


Then  in  order  to  diminish  the  eccentricity  it  is  sufficient  that 

<*+/?>!. 

In  this  case  even  if  /3  =  0  (that  is,  if  the  resistance  R  does  not  vary 
with  the  distance  r  from  the  sun)  we  need  only  have 


that  is  to  say,  R  increasing  more  rapidly  than  the  simple  power  of 
the  velocity.  Now  we  often  grant  as  an  approximation  that  a  medial 
resistance  is  proportionate  to  the  square  of  the  velocity. 

This  diminution  of  the  eccentricity  because  of  a  medial  resis- 
tance might  have  been  foreseen  in  general  and  without  calculation  in 
the  following  manner.  Suppose  the  resistance  is  not  felt  except  in 
the  vicinity  of  the  perihelion  P  (Fig.  1).  In  that  case  the  planet 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  467 

undergoes  at  this  point  P  a  sudden  diminution  of  velocity  which  re- 
sults in  a  decrease  in  the  major  axis.  Since  the  perihelion  remains 
the  same  and  the  aphelion  approaches  it,  it  is  clear  that  the  eccen- 
tricity is  lessened.  On  the  other  hand,  if  resistance  acts  only  at  the 
moment  of  the  aphelion,  the  new  orbit  would  have  the  same  aphelion 
as  the  former  one,  but  its  perihelion  would  be  nearer  that  of  the 
sun,  and  the  eccentricity  would  be  increased.  In  fact  the  resistance 
is  felt  all  along  the  orbit,  but  two  reasons  combine  to  make  it  felt 
more  strongly  at  the  perihelion:  in  the  first  place  the  velocity  is 
greatest  at  that  point,  since  the  atmosphere  which  is  generally  denser 
nearer  the  sun  offers  a  greater  resistance  near  the  perihelion. 

To  sum  up,  the  effect  of  medial  resistance  on  a  Keplerian  orbit 
is  to  diminish  both  the  major  axis  and  the  eccentricity.5  Therefore 
if  we  agree  with  Mr.  See  that  a  resisting  atmosphere  originally 
extended  for  vast  distances  around  the  sun,  we  can  conceive  that  a 


Fig.  i. 

body  of  cosmical  origin  when  passing  into  the  sun's  sphere  of  in- 
fluence might  be  able  to  modify  its  trajectory.  Whether  it  was 
parabolic  or  hyperbolic  it  now  becomes  elliptical,  because  the  medial 
resistance  continues  to  diminish  the  major  axis  and  the  eccentricity 
of  the  orbit  which  approaches  the  circular  form.  The  resisting  at- 
mosphere is  gradually  absorbed  by  the  sun,  and  when  it  finally  dis- 
appears the  smaller  body  continues  to  revolve  around  the  sun  in  its 
orbit  which  is  almost  a  circle.  Such,  according  to  Mr.  See,  is  the 
history  of  all  the  planets. 

Just  as  the  planets  have  been  captured  by  the  sun  so  also,  ac- 
cording to  Mr.  See,  have  the  satellites,  been  captured  by  their  respec- 
tive planets.6 

In  order  to  study  this  capture  we  shall  take  up  the  comparatively 
simple  case  called  the  restricted  problem.  The  sun  S  and  a  planet  J 

8  It  is  easy  to  recognize  that  this  resistance  does  not  produce  any  secular 
effect  (at  least  at  the  first  approximation)  on  the  longitude  of  the  perihelion. 
To  be  sure  it  does  not  modify  the  plane  of  the  orbit  which  retains  the  same 
inclination  and  the  same  line  of  nodes  with  reference  to  a  fixed  plane. 

8  Loc,  cit.,  Chap.  VIII,  pp.  159-182;  X,  pp  211-236. 


468  THE  MONIST. 

(e.  g.,  Jupiter)  each  revolve  around  their  common  center  of  gravity 
G  in  a  circular  orbit  with  a  constant  angular  velocity  w  (Fig.  2).  It 
is  required  to  study  the  motion  of  a  small  planet  P  whose  mass  is 
negligible  with  reference  to  that  of  the  principal  planet  J  and  which 
consequently  will  not  affect  the  motion  of  the  latter.  We  will  take 
as  origin  the  center  of  gravity  G,  of  the  system  S  -  J  ;  as  plane  of 
the  coordinates  xy,  the  plane  in  which  S  and  J  describe  their  circular 
orbits  ;  and  in  this  plane  rectangular  movable  axes,  the  axis  of  x 
being  the  straight  line  SGJ  which  connects  the  sun  with  Jupiter; 
the  axis  of  z  is  the  perpendicular  to  the  plane  of  the  orbit  at  G.  The 
forces  acting  actually  upon  the  point  P  (x,  y,  z)  are  the  attraction 
of  the  sun  and  of  Jupiter.  These  two  forces  are  derived  respectively 
from  the  two  functions  of  forces7 


Pi  PZ 


S          G  J 

Fig.  2. 

M!,  M2  being  the  masses  of  the  sun  and  Jupiter,  plf  p2  their  distances 
from  P.  Since  the  axes  are  movable  we  must  add  to  these  forces  the 
centrifugal  force  and  the  compound  centrifugal  force.  The  com- 
ponents of  the  centrifugal  force  are 

The  components  of  the  compound  centrifugal  force  are 


Hence  the  equations  of  the  motion  of  the  planet  P  with  relation  to 
the  movable  axes  are 


7  We  assume  the  mass  m  of  the  small  planet  P  to  be  equal  to  unity.  More 
exactly,  since  this  mass  m  is  a  factor  in  every  case  we  shall  not  write  it  in 
the  formulas. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 


469 


dt2  ~~  ds       dz  ' 
If  we  multiply  these  three  equations 


respectively,  and  add  the  results,  we  obtain  a  combination  imme- 
diately integrable  which  brings  us  to  the  following  integral 

)1VJ-1        jLVJ-2  /      o  o  \         s-~\ 

=  —  +  —  +  -0  (x2+y2)-C, 
J      Pi      P2      2 

known  by  the  name  of  the  integral  of  Jacobi. 

Since  the  first  member  of  this  last  equation  is  positive,  the  co- 
ordinates x,  y,  z  of  the  point  P  will  satisfy  the  inequality 


2+  2)_c>0_ 


X. 


Fig.  3- 

Hence  the  projection  (x,  y)  of  the  point  P  on  the  plane  of  xy 
will  be  within  the  curve 


in  this  equation  pl  and  p2  denoting  the  distances  of  this  projection 
of  the  point  P  from  the  points  S  and  J.  For  very  great  values  of 
the  constant  C  this  curve  comprises  two  rings  (denoted  by  1  on 
Fig.  3)  surrounding  the  points  S  and  J  respectively.  As  C  dimin- 
ishes, these  two  rings  become  dilated  and  finally  unite  at  a  double 
point  A  (Curve  2).  Then  when  C  is  further  diminished  they  finally 
make  only  one  curve  (Curve  3)  surrounding  at  the  same  time  both 
S  and  J.8  Hence  when  the  constant  C  is  not  too  great  the  small 
planet  is  obliged  to  remain  within  Curve  3  but  still  is  free  to  travel 
in  the  proximity  either  of  the  sun  or  of  Jupiter.  On  the  contrary 

8  We  pay  no  attention  here  to  certain  portions  of  curves  which  are  very 
far  removed  from  the  origin. 


470  THE   MONIST. 

if  the  constant  C  is  very  great  the  small  planet  will  remain  within 
one  of  the  rings  1 ;  it  will  be  a  satellite  either  of  the  sun  or  of 
Jupiter. 

Now  the  effect  of  a  passive  resistance  like  that  of  a  medium 
is  to  increase  the  constant  C  of  the  second  member  of  Jacobi's  in- 
tegral. Hence  the  curve  encircling  the  small  planet  constantly  con- 
tracts. If  it  was  originally  Curve  3  at  a  definite  moment  it  will 
become  Curve  2  with  the  double  point.  If  at  this  moment  the  planet 
is  near  the  sun  it  will  never  return  to  the  proximity  of  Jupiter;  it 
is  captured  by  the  sun.  If  on  the  contrary  it  is  in  the  neighborhood 
of  Jupiter  it  will  never  return  to  that  of  the  sun ;  it  will  be  captured 
by  Jupiter  and  from  that  moment  will  become  one  of  his  satellites. 

The  theory  of  Mr.  See  accounts  for  the  smallness  of  the  eccen- 
tricities of  the  orbits  of  planets  and  satellites.9  But  why  are  the 
movements  of  almost  all  the  heavenly  bodies  in  a  straight  line,  and 
why  have  their  orbits  such  small  mutual  inclinations?  In  the  hy- 
pothesis of  Mr.  See  these  two  questions  remain  without  any  satis- 
factory answer.  To  try  to  explain  the  smallness  of  the  inclinations 
we  may  suppose  that  the  resisting  atmosphere  of  the  sun  is  of  a 
greatly  flattened  lenticular  form ;  hence  a  body  whose  orbit  is  greatly 
inclined  to  the  plane  of  this  disk  suffers  a  resistance  much  smaller 
than  a  body  moving  in  the  very  plane  of  the  disk.  The  first  body 
has  therefore  much  less  tendency  to  be  captured  than  the  second, 
and  is  in  the  plane  of  the  disk  in  which  the  captures  of  the  planets 
are  made. 

We  may  also  suppose  that  the  resisting  medium  itself  revolves. 
It  will  then  tend  not  to  counteract  the  velocity  of  the  planet  revolving 
within  it  but  to  impose  upon  this  planet  a  certain  velocity.  Since 
the  resistance  is  no  longer  directly  opposed  to  the  velocity,  the  plane 
of  the  orbit  could  vary  and  tend  to  diminish  its  inclination  to  the 
equatorial  plane  of  the  solar  atmosphere. 

FORMATION  OF  SPIRAL  NEBULAS. 

In  the  work  previously  referred  to,10  Mr.  See  is  concerned  with 
the  formation  of  nebulas,  especially  with  the  origin  of  spiral  nebulas. 

Let  us  imagine  two  masses  of  cosmical  vapor  N  and  N',  almost 
equal  in  size  and  traveling  in  opposite  directions  (Fig.  4a).  As  they 

9  The  diminution  of  the  eccentricity  because  of  a  resisting  medium  is  of 
first  importance  not  only  in  the  theory  of  Mr.  See ;  it  is  taken  into  considera- 
tion also  in  the  theories  of  Faye  and  of  Du  Ligondes. 

10  Op.  cit.,  Chap.  XIX. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  471 

approach  each  other  their  adjacent  extremities  will  be  prolonged 
each  in  the  direction  of  the  other  by  mutual  attraction  (Fig.  46) 
and  may  even  end  in  uniting  to  form  a  single  body  (Fig.  4c)  near 
whose  center  attraction  combined  with  friction  will  tend  to  produce 
a  condensation,  a  sort  of  central  nucleus.  The  two  masses  of  vapor 
N  and  N'  will  turn  in  the  directions  of  the  arrows  around  this  center 
like  two  arms  of  a  windmill. 

Such,  according  to  Mr.  See,  would  be  the  origin  of  the  spiral 
nebulas.    The  central  nucleus  would  tend  to  enlarge  more  and  more 


N 


Fig.  4. 


at  the  expense  of  the  matter  in  the  two  spiral  branches  N  and  N'. 
Hence  we  see  that  in  the  opinion  of  Mr.  See  the  motion  of  the 
matter  in  the  two  arms  of  the  spiral  nebula  contrary  to  the  usual 
view  would  be  centripetal  and  not  centrifugal.  Moreover  whether 
the  motion  is  convergent  or  divergent  the  law  of  areas  accounts 
equally  in  both  cases  for  the  slowness  of  the  arm's  revolution  around 
its  pivot,  that  is  to  say,  the  spiral  form  of  both  arms. 

It  may  happen  that  the  ends  of  the  two  masses  of  vapor  N  and 
N'  do  not  join  as  they  approach  each  other,  but  are  merely  deviated 
by  attraction.  Then  the  phase  following  phase  2  of  Fig.  4.  is  not 


N 

Fig.  5- 

phase  c  but  phase  d  (Fig.  5)  after  which  it  assumes  phase  e.  In 
such  a  case  we  have  the  origin  of  an  annular  nebula  like  that  of 
Lyra.  In  the  two  diametrically  opposed  light  portions  seen  in  the 
ring  of  Lyra,  Mr.  See  finds  an  argument  for  the  application  of  this 
theory  in  that  adjacent  ends  of  the  two  masses  of  vapor  N  and  N' 
would  not  be  perfectly  united. 

Hence  Mr.  See  thinks  that  an  annular  nebula  is  formed  by  the 
same  mechanical  process  as  spiral  nebulas  of  which  it  thus  proves 
to  be  in  some  sense  a  particular  case.  But  the  annular  form  is 


472  THE  MONIST. 

very  rare  because  the  conditions  for  the  formation  of  a  perfect  ring 
are  not  often  realized. 

One  great  objection  may  be  offered  to  this  theory.  The  tw« 
arms  of  a  spiral  nebula  are  usually  almost  symmetrical.  In  the 
ordinary  hypothesis  in  which  the  movement  of  the  arms  is  assumed 
to  be  divergent  this  symmetry  ma"  be  explained  by  the  common 
origin  of  the  two  arms.  In  the  hypothesis  of  Mr.  See  there  is  no 
wray  to  account  for  it,  for  the  two  masses  of  cosmical  vapor  N  and 
N'  which  give  rise  to  the  nebula  and  which  have  met  accidentally  will 
not  usually  be  equal.  They  ought  then  to  give  birth  to  an  unsym- 
metrical  nebula. 

Mr.  See  thinks  that  originally  the  solar  system  was  a  spiral 
nebula  of  vast  extent.  The  matter  at  its  center  first  became  agglom- 
erated into  particles  which  with  the  help  of  the  resistance  of  the 
medium  were  condensed  into  asteroids,  according  to  the  process  ex- 
plained above,  and  then  into  planets,  which  are  further  increased  by 
bombardment.11 

Mr.  See  is  led  by  analogy  to  believe  that  the  spiral  nebulas 
which  are  less  advanced  in  their  evolution  than  the  solar  system  are 
composed  of  a  vast  number  of  very  small  bodies  like  the  planets  or 
even  the  moon.  If  we  can  not  analyze  these  nebulas  it  will  be  be- 
cause of  the  extremely  small  size  of  their  component  parts  and  not 
because  these  celestial  objects  are  so  excessively  remote.  Mr.  Bohlin 
has  tried  to  measure  the  parallax  of  the  nebula  of  Andromeda  (which 
is  a  spiral  nebula  of  a  continuous  spectrum)  and  he  has  found  it 
equal  to  0",  17,  so  that  this  nebula  would  be  comparatively  very  near 
us.  But  considering  how  little  accuracy  the  points  on  the  nebulas 
admit  of,  can  we  regard  this  observation  as  conclusive  and  certain? 

H.  POINCARE. 

PARIS,  FRANCE. 

NOTES  ON  THE  CONSTRUCTION  OF  MAGIC  SQUARES 

OF  ORDERS  IN  WHICH  11  IS  OF  THE  FORM  8/>  +  2. 

Referring  to  the  article  in  the  last  issue  of  The  Monist  by 
Messrs.  Andrews  and  Frierson,  under  the  above  heading,  it  was 
shown  that  the  minimum  series  to  be  used  in  constructing  this 
class  of  squares  is  selected  from  the  series  1,  2,  3, (w+3)2,  by 

11  Mr.  See  sees  in  the  lunar  craters  signs  of  a  bombardment  produced  at 
the  surface  of  the  moon  by  the  fall  of  a  large  number  of  little  satellites.  He 
compares  these  craters  to  the  marks  left  by  great  drops  of  rain  in  the  mud 
(op.  cit.,  p.  342,  plate  XII). 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 


473 


discarding  3  rows  and  columns  from  the  natural  square  of  the  order 
n  +  3. 

It  is  not  necessary,  however,  to  discard  the  three  central  rows 
and   columns,   as   was    therein    explained,   there    being    numerous 

variations,  the  total  number  of  which  is  always  equal  to  ( — -r—  \ 


Fig.  i. 


Fig.  2. 


Fig.  3- 


Fig.  4. 


Fig.  5- 


Fig.  6. 


Fig.  7-  Fig.  8.  Fig.  9. 

therefore  the  102  can  be  constructed  with  9  different  series,  the  182 
with  25  different  series,  the  262  with  49  different  series,  and  so  on. 

In  Figs.  1  to  ,9  are  shown  all  the  possible  variations  of  dis- 
carding rows  and  columns  for  the  102,  Fig.  I  representing  the  series 
explained  in  the  foregoing  article. 

The  central  row  and  column  must  always  be  discarded,  the 
remaining  two  rows  and  columns  can  be  cast  out  symmetrically  in 
relation  to  their  parallel  central  row  or  column  and  should  be  an 


474 


THE   MONIST. 


odd  number  of  rows  or  columns  from  it.     In  other  words,  we  cast 
out  the  central  row,  then  on  each  side  of  it  we  cast  out  the  1st,  3d, 


vO 
to 

NO 

to 

VO 
VO 

•* 

2 

O 

co 

CM 

s 

vo 

vO 

- 

ON 

NO 

^ 

NO 

ON 

S 

ON 

5 

X 

2 

8 

CM 

vo 

s 

s 

CM 
vo 

N 

td 

Ld 

^ 

1 

J 

td 

o 

0 

ON 

id 

o 

o 

ON 

w 

0 

on 

LJ 

CM 

< 

td 

co 

H 

jj 

- 

S 

WJ 

9 

td 

s 

•*> 

CO 

U 

td 

to 

vO 

NO 

0 

a 

on 

CM 

to 

u. 

10 

*"* 

CM 

to 

*J 

ON 

NO 

o 

£ 

O 

ON 

NO 

to 

O 

CM 

•* 

(N 

CM 

2 

2 

O 

•^HMM 
MHHMM 

o 

0 

•MMMM 

~ 

2 

^ 

^ 

~ 

T* 

^ 

o 

VO 

ON 

00 

NO 

0 

NO 

00 

Ov 

* 

0 

< 

o. 

to 

CO 

ON 

ON 

to 

(  ) 

td 

00 

. 

td 

CX5 

rO 

iii 

(tl 

[T} 

—  ! 

w 

j 

5 

«*< 

* 

O 

z 

5 

td 

CO 

s 

^ 

5 

Id 

« 

O 

o 

t_l 

LM 

m 

u 

NO 

U 

NO 

u 

to 

CM 

••* 

on 

to 

CM 

*^ 

ftS 

vo 

CO 

•• 

UJ 

a: 

« 

CO 

_ 

CO 

^ 

« 

CO 

^ 

CO 

CM 

c^ 

mmumrn 

m*mmm* 

l^iHB^ 

5th,  or  7th,  etc.  rows  from  it,  and  irrespective  of  the  rows,  we  do 
likewise  with  the  columns. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 


475 


In  a  manner  already  explained,  numbers  are  selected  according 
to  the  series  desired  and  arranged  in  rectangles  with  which  the 
magic  square  is  constructed. 

A   set  of  rectangles   with  their  respective  series   is   shown 
Fig.  10,  and  the  following  table  will  give  directions  for  their  use. 


in 


SERIES 


RECTANGLES  (See  Fig.  10) 


Fig.  1 


Fig.  2 
Fig.  3 
Fig.  4 
Fig.  5 
Fig.  6 
Fig.  7 
Fig.  8 
Fig.  9 

A  and  X 
B  and  X 
C  and  X 
A  and  Y 
B  and  Y 
C  and  Y 
A  and  Z 
B  and  Z 
C  and  Z 

Fig.  ii. 

For  example,  suppose  we  were  to  construct  a  square,  using  the 
series  denoted  in  Fig.  3.  By  referring  to  the  table  it  is  seen  that  we 
must  employ  rectangles  C  and  X.  By  using  the  La  Hireian  method 
these  rectangles  are  placed  as  shown  in  Fig.  11,  care  being  taken  to 
arrange  them  in  respect  to  the  final  square,  whether  it  is  to  be  asso- 
ciated or  non-associated.1 

A  non-associated  square  resulting  from  rectangles  C  and  X  is 
shown  in  Fig.  12.  Another  example  by  Mr.  Andrews,  using  the 
path  method  is  shown  in  Figs.  13,  14  and  15.  Here  a  series  corres- 

1  See  preceding  article. 


THE   MONIST. 


ponding  to  Fig.  8  has  been  selected  and  the  natural  square  is  shown 
in  Fig.  13,  the  heavy  lines  indicating  the  discarded  rows  and  col- 
umns. The  rows  and  columns  are  re-arranged  according  to  the  nu- 


6S 

/07 

S6 

//3 

SB 

f/7 

SS 

/OS 

6/ 

f/O 

40 

/28 

43 

/22 

47 

//8 

SO 

/27 

44- 

/2S 

/43 

29 

/34 

3S 

/36 

39 

/33 

30 

/39 

32 

/4 

/S4 

23 

/48 

2/ 

/44 

24- 

/S3 

/£ 

/S/ 

/6? 

3 

/60 

9 

/6Z 

/3 

/S? 

^ 

/6S 

6 

S3 

US 

62 

/09 

60 

/OS 

63 

//^ 

S? 

//2 

sz 

/20 

4-3 

/26 

4S 

/30 

42 

/2/ 

1-8 

S23 

<3/ 

37 

/4O 

3f 

t38 

27 

&/ 

36 

MS 

3+ 

26 

/46 

17 

/S2 

/^ 

/S6 

/6 

/*7 

22 

/49 

/& 

// 

/66 

S 

/64 

/ 

&7 

/O 

/<£/ 

8 

Fig.   12. 


/ 

2 

3 

S 

<^ 

8 

3 

// 

/2 

& 

27 

Z8 

Z<? 

3/ 

32 

34 

3S 

37 

38 

39 

40 

41 

42 

44 

4S 

47 

+8 

SO 

S/ 

SZ 

S3 

S4 

SS 

S7 

S3 

60 

6/ 

63 

64 

6S 

66 

67 

68 

70 

71 

73 

74 

76 

77 

78 

3Z 

?3 

94 

96 

97 

93 

/oo 

/02 

/O3 

/04 

/OS 

/06 

/o? 

tod 

//O 

H2 

//3 

//S 

//6 

//7 

//S 

1/9 

/20 

/22 

/23 

/2S 

/26 

/28 

t29 

/30 

131 

/32 

/33 

/3S 

/36 

<3S 

'39 

W 

W2 

/43 

/S7 

/S8 

/& 

/£/ 

f6Z 

/64 

/6S 

/67 

/68 

/69 

Fig.  13. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 


477 


merical  sequence  of  the  continuous  diagonals1  of  rectangles  B  and  Z 
of  Fig.  10,  this  re-arrangement  being  shown  in  Fig.  14. 


/ 

Z 

// 

9 

6 

/3 

/Z 

3 

J- 

6 

Z7 

ze 

37 

3S 

3Z 

39 

38 

23 

31 

34- 

t!8 

/I9 

/28 

/26 

/23 

/30 

/2& 

/2O 

/22 

/2S 

/OS 

/06 

f/S 

//3 

//o 

//7 

//6 

to? 

/09 

//Z 

?2 

23 

/OZ 

/OO 

97 

/O4- 

/03 

?# 

?& 

?? 

,s? 

/Sg 

/e>7 

/6S 

/6Z 

/6<? 

/68 

/&? 

/<£/ 

/64- 

/3/ 

/3Z 

/*/ 

/3? 

/36 

/4-3 

/4Z 

/33 

/or 

/3S 

40 

4-1 

So 

+8 

4-S 

S2 

S/ 

4Z 

4*4- 

4-7 

S3 

S4- 

63 

6/ 

S8 

6S 

64- 

fS 

S7 

60 

££ 

67 

76 

74- 

71 

73 

77 

63 

70 

73 

Fig.   14. 


s 

/6Z 

/ 

/6S 

// 

(6/ 

6 

^7 

iZ 

/67 

/CO 

73 

/04- 

67 

94- 

74- 

9? 

78 

93 

68 

S7 

//O 

S3 

//6 

63 

/03 

jra 

/OS 

64- 

//S 

tZ6 

4-7 

/30 

4-1 

/20 

44 

/2S 

S2 

/& 

4Z 

/3S 

32 

/3I 

38 

/4-I 

3/ 

/36 

27 

/4-2 

37 

9 

/6+ 

/3 

/& 

3 

/6S 

B 

/69 

2 

/& 

?6 

71 

9Z 

77 

/OZ 

70 

97 

66 

/03 

76 

61 

//Z 

6S 

/06 

SS 

//3 

60 

//7 

&- 

S07 

I2Z 

4S 

//S 

S/ 

/Z8 

4-4- 

fZ3 

40 

/2? 

SO 

139 

34* 

#3 

28 

/33 

3S 

/3S 

33 

/3Z 

Z? 

Fig.   15. 
1  See  article  in  Monist  of  April,  1912. 


478  THE  MONIST. 

In  constructing  the  final  square,  Fig.  15,  an  advance  move  -4, 
-5  and  a  break  move  1,  1  was  used. 

It  wiil  be  unnecessary  to  show  examples  of  higher  orders  of 
these  squares,  as  their  methods  of  construction  are  only  extensions 
of  what  has  been  already  described.  It  may  be  mentioned  that  these 
squares  when  non-associated  can  be  transformed  into  associated 
squares  by  the  method  given  in  Messrs.  Andrews  and  Frierson's 
article.  HARRY  A.  SAYLES. 

SCHENECTADY,    N.    Y. 

POSTSCRIPT  ON  BUDDHISM  AND  CHRISTIANITY. 

My  article  on  the  "Contributions  of  Buddhism  to  Christianity," 
which  appeared  in  The  Monist  of  October,  1911,  called  forth  two 
criticisms  in  the  following  number  (January  1912).  One  was  by 
Albert  J.  Edmunds,  "Buddhist  Loans  to  Christianity,"  pp.  129  ff., 
and  the  other  by  Wilfred  H.  Schoff,  "First  Century  Intercourse 
Between  India  and  Rome,"  pp.  138  ff. 

Even  before  these  criticisms  reached  me,  I  began  to  doubt 
whether  my  standpoint  that  Buddhist  influences  were  "not  yet  to  be 
found  in  the  canonical  Gospels,  but  first  in  the  Apocryphal  Gospels," 
could  be  maintained  in  this  categorical  form.1  The  historical  possi- 
bility for  the  infiltration  of  Buddhist  material  into  the  canonical 
Gospels  I  have  never  denied,  but  only  its  probability.  I  take  pleas- 
ure in  using  this  opportunity  to  grant  that  by  the  lucid  critique  of 
Edmunds  the  probability  of  the  hypothesis  of  Buddhist  loans  in  the 
New  Testament  has  increased  in  my  opinion. 

The  connection  of  the  Asita-Simeon  parallel  with  the  praise  of 
the  heavenly  hosts  in  both  the  Suttanipata  and  in  the  Gospel  of  Luke 
has  strongly  impressed  me  even  though  I  can  not  concede  to  Ed- 
munds that  this  connection  is  an  "organic"  one  on  both  sides.  The 
connection  is  organic  only  in  the  Pali  source  and  not  in  Luke,  where 
in  the  second  chapter  the  Simeon  story  does  not  stand  in  an  intrinsic 
connection  with  the  angelic  hymn  but  only  near  it.  But  even  this 
correspondence  is  certainly  remarkable  enough. 

The  exposition  which  Edmunds  has  given  of  the  temptation 
parallels  ( Samyuttanikaya  and  Luke  iv.  1-2)  also  decidedly  increases 
the  probability  of  the  loan  hypothesis.  Because  of  this  the  Buddhist 
origin  of  some  other  New  Testament  stories,  to  which  I  have  here- 
tofore only  with  hesitancy  granted  a  remote  possibility  that  they 

1  See  my  article,  "Buddhistisches  im  Neuen  Testament,"  in  Das  Freie 
Wort,  Frankfort,  December  1911,  pp.  674  ff. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  479 

might  have  been  borrowed  from  India,  also  becomes  of  course  more 
probable. 

Edmunds  is  entirely  mistaken  in  his  explanation  of  the  Wander- 
ing Jew  (pp.  137-138). 2  Mark  ix.  1 :  "Verily  I  say  unto  you,  There 
be  some  here  of  them  that  stand  by,  who  shall  in  no  wise  taste  of 
death,  till  they  see  the  kingdom  of  God  come  with  power,"  does  not 
in  the  least  contain  the  germ  of  this  legend  but  simply  expresses 
like  the  other  passages  on  the  Parousia  ( Matt.  x.  23 ;  xvi.  28 ;  Luke 
ix.  27)  the  conviction  of  Jesus  that  the  end  of  the  world  was  at 
hand. 

The  article  of  W.  H.  Schoff  elucidates  in  a  clear  exposition 
well-known  facts  about  the  commercial  intercourse  between  India 
and  the  Occident  in  the  first  century  after  Christ,  but  he  brings  no 
positive  proof  that  an  exchange  of  ideas  necessarily  went  hand  in 
hand  with  the  extensive  commercial  intercourse.  Especially,  he,  as 
the  translator  of  the  Periplus,  ought  to  have  inferred  from  this  text 
that  the  mariners  and  traders  of  those  days  had  but  little  thought 
for  anything  but  their  merchandise.  The  author  of  the  Periplus, 
who  describes  his  journey  to  India  between  70  and  75  A.  D.,  treated 
only  of  what  would  be  interesting  to  the  merchant  and  mariner,  but 
otherwise  shows  that  he  was  uninformed  about  the  most  common- 
place things  and  says  not  one  word  about  religion.  Likewise  the 
Indian  merchants  who  had  settled  in  Alexandria  were  according  to 
the  testimony  of  Dio  Chrysostom  (Orat.  35)  ignorant  people  and 
probably  of  Dravidian  race.  They  would  have  taken  no  more  inter- 
est in  religious  questions  than  the  Greek  or  Roman  merchants  of 
their  time. 

When  Schoff  (page  141)  describes  the  merchants  as  "bearing 
ideas  no  less  than  goods,"  this  is  simply  begging  the  question. 

More  important  for  our  purpose  than  all  reports  of  ancient 
commercial  relations  seems  to  me  the  observation  of  Max  Miiller 
expressed  in  the  following  words:3  "Though  we  have  no  tangible 
evidence  of  anything  like  translations,  whether  Oriental  or  Occi- 
dental, at  that  time,  we  seem  perfectly  within  our  right  when  we 
look  upon  the  numerous  coincidences  between  the  fables  of  ^Esop 
and  the  fables  occurring  in  Sanskrit  and  Pali  literature  as  proving 
the  fact  that  there  was  a  real  literary  exchange  between  India,  Per- 
sia, Asia  Minor  and  Greece  beginning  with  the  6th  century  B.  C." 

TUBINGEN,  GERMANY.  R.  GARBE. 

2  Compare  also  Buddhist  and  Christian  Gospels,  4th  ed.,  II,  pp.  264  ff. 

3  In  the  article  "Coincidences"  in  Last  Essays,  I,  269-270. 


480  THE  MONIST. 

POINCARE'S  COSMOGONIC  HYPOTHESES. 

Prof.  H.  Poincare  has  just  published  an  important  book1  which 
treats  the  interesting  problem  of  the  origin  of  the  world  according 
to  the  scientific  views  of  modern  philosophers  and  naturalists.  Pro- 
fessor Poincare  in  the  first  chapter  discusses  Kant's  hypothesis  and 
subjects  it  to  a  critical  analysis.  The  second  chapter  is  devoted  to 
La  Place;  the  third  analyzes  La  Place's  hypothesis  and  discusses 
the  work  of  La  Roche,  especially  the  theory  of  the  stability  of 
rings  and  the  formation  of  satellites.  Subdivisions  of  this  third 
chapter  treat  the  hypothesis  of  a  uniform  notation,  the  rings  of 
Saturn,  the  rupture  of  rings  according  to  La  Place  and  the  forma- 
tion of  planets  and  satellites,  and  the  author  sums  up  the  objections 
to  the  theory  of  La  Place. 

The  fourth  chapter  is  devoted  to  the  hypothesis  of  H.  Faye, 
according  to  which  the  earth  is  much  older  than  the  sun.  Chapter 
five  discusses  the  hypothesis  of  du  Ligondes  who  claims  that  Kant's 
hypothesis  stand  in  contradiction  to  the  principle  of  the  gases.  The 
sixth  chapter  treats  the  hypothesis  of  Prof.  T.  J.  J.  See,  which  will 
be  of  special  interest  to  American  readers  because  he  is  a  native 
American  and  is  the  astronomer  of  the  Naval  Observatory,  Mare 
Island,  California.  This  chapter  together  with  the  thirteenth  is 
reproduced  in  an  English  translation  on  another  page  of  this  issue. 
The  seventh  chapter  discusses  the  theory  of  Sir  George  Howard  Dar- 
win, his  theory  of  tides,  especially  the  internal  tides  of  the  earth, 
the  accelerative  influence  of  cooling  down,  and  his  hypothesis  of 
the  formation  of  the  moon.  The  eighth  chapter  treats  the  theory 
of  solar  and  terrestrial  heat,  as  well  as  the  adiabatic  equilibrium  of  a 
perfect  gas. 

Chapter  nine  treats  of  the  theory  of  Sir  Norman  Lockyer, 
Chapter  ten  of  Schuster  and  Chapter  eleven  of  Arrhenius's  theories ; 
Chapter  twelve  compares  the  mass  of  the  Milky  Way  with  a  gaseous 
mass.  Its  substance  is  comparable  to  the  radiant  matter  of  Krookes, 
rather  than  to  a  true  gas.  He  then  treats  possible  causes  of  the 
flattening  of  the  Milky  Way  and  concludes  with  a  consideration  of 
the  star  clusters  of  Kapteyn  and  Schiaparelli. 

In  the  thirteenth  chapter  our  author  returns  to  Professor  See 
and  discusses  his  view  of  the  formation  of  the  nebular  spirals ;  and 
the  last  chapter  is  devoted  to  the  hypothesis  of  Emile  Belot.  P.  c. 

1  Lemons  sur  les  hypotheses  cosmogonlques.    Paris:  Hermann,  1911.    Price 
12  francs. 


VOL.  XXII.  OCTOBER,  1912.  NO.  4 

THE  MONIST 


FOR  LOGISTICS.1 

INTRODUCTORY  NOTE. M.  POINCARE  AND  M.  COUTURAT. 

Soon  after  Mr.  Bertrand  Russell's  Principles  of  Mathematics  of 
1903  was  published,  M.  Louis  Couturat  gave  an  exceedingly  inter- 
esting popular  account  of  this  and  other  works  in  the  Revue  de 
Metaphysique  et  de  Morale  for  1904  and  1905,  which  was  afterwards 
published  in  book  form  in  19052  with  an  appendix  on  Kant's  philos- 
ophy of  mathematics  read  at  the  celebrations  in  1904  of  the  cen- 
tenary of  the  death  of  Kant.  Then  M.  Henri  Poincare  thought  fit 
to  publish,  in  the  above  Revue t  a  series  of  articles  of  which  this  is 
a  list : 

"Les  mathematiques  et  la  logique,"  Revue,  Vol.  XIII,  1905, 
pp.  815-835;  Vol.  XIV,  1906,  pp.  17-34;  and  ibid.,  pp.  294-314;  "La 
logique  de  1'infmi,"  ibid.,  Vol.  XVII,  1909,  pp.  461-482. 

In  connection  with  some  of  the  subjects  so  lightly  and  grace- 
fully touched  upon  by  M.  Poincare  appeared  the  following: 

Mario  Pieri,  "Sur  la  compatibilite  des  axiomes  de  1'arithme- 
tique,"  Rev.  de  Metaphys.,  Vol.  XIV,  1906,  pp.  196-207. 

Louis  Couturat,  "Pour  la  Logistique  (reponse  a  M.  Poincare)/' 
ibid.,  pp.  208-250. 

B.  Russell,  "Les  paradoxes  de  la  logique,"  ibid.,  pp.  627-650. 

The  writings  of  M.  Poincare  are  well  known  to  the  readers  of 
The  Monist.  His  criticisms  are  refreshingly  light  and  gay  and  he 
never  allows  profundity  to  obscure  his  wit.  It  is,  however,  un- 
fortunate that  his  airy  remarks  on  modern  logic — which,  by  the 
way,  he  confesses  rather  needlessly  that  he  has  not  studied — have 
been  taken  so  seriously  by  many.  It  is,  as  newspaper  editors  know,  a 
tendency  of  the  public  to  read  with  interest  and  even  to  accept  un- 
critically the  opinions  of  an  eminent  person  on  matters  about  which 
he  is  not  an  expert.  The  views  of  a  well-known  football  player  on 

1  Translated  by  Philip  E.  B.  Jourdain. 

a  Les  principes  des  mathematiques  avec  un  appendice  sur  la  philosophic  des 
mathematiques  de  Kant. 


482  THE  MONIST. 

the  science  of  anatomy  would  no  doubt  be  widely  read,  and  the 
views  of  M.  Poincare  on  the  philosophical  questions  at  the  root  of 
mathematics  are  not,  in  essentials,  of  a  very  different  nature.  It 
is  part  of  the  business  of  anatomy  to  study  deeply  these  faculties 
which  the  athlete  uses  unconsciously.  The  analogy  is  quite  evident. 
M.  Poincare  is  one  of  our  greatest  mathematicians,  and  centuries 
have  proved  that  a  man  who  is  a  great  mathematician  need  be 
neither  a  great  philosopher  nor  a  great  logician.  We  do  not  expect 
such  a  combination  of  qualities, nor,  as  a  rule,  do  we  find  them. 

M.  Louis  Couturat  gave  a  very  full  and  adequate  reply  to  the 
first  two  of  M.  Poincare's  articles.  In  spite  of  this  M.  Poincare  re- 
produced, in  the  same  words,  his  refuted  arguments  in  his  lately 
published  book  Science  et  Methode.  The  chapter  entitled  "Les 
Mathematiques  et  la  Logique"  on  pp.  152-171  of  the  book  is  almost 
identical  with  pp.  815-824  of  the  first  article;  the  chapter  entitled 
"Les  Logiques  nouvelles"  on  pp.  172-196,  which  is  that  translated  on 
pp.  243-256  of  The  Monist  for  April,  1912,  is  an  abridged  version 
of  pp.  826-835  of  the  first  paper  and  the  second  article.  The  chapter 
entitled  "Les  derniers  efforts  des  Logisticiens"  on  pp.  192-214  re- 
produces much  of  the  less  technical  parts  of  his  third  article,  and 
this  article,  which  is  translated  in  the  present  number,  was  replied 
to  by  Mr.  Russell  in  his  above  cited  paper. 

The  fourth  article  of  M.  Poincare  is  concerned  principally  with 
a  memoir  on  the  theory  of  "logical  types"  published  by  Russell  in 
1908  and  with  one  on  the  foundations  of  the  theory  of  aggregates 
published  by  Zermelo  in  the  same  year. 

It  is  quite  obvious  that  nobody  should  allow  himself  to  speak 
or  write  in  terms  of  approval  or  disparagement  of  a  branch  of  study 
with  which  he  has  only  a  superficial  acquaintance.  Each  of  us  is 
free  to  dislike  or  like  a  particular  subject  and  to  leave  it  alone  or  to 
cultivate  it  accordingly,  and  if  he  finds  good  reasons  for  so  doing  he 
ought  to  publish  them.  But  not  even  the  most  eminent  can  really 
think  that  a  brightly  written  condemnation  of  a  subject,  based  on 
a  very  superficial  acquaintance  with  it,  is  of  any  real  value.  Indeed, 
the  more  eminent  a  person  is,  the  more  able  he  generally  is  to 
prevent  us  from  seeing  the  truth.  And  then,  besides  the  thought 
of  the  efforts  of  others  to  perceive  the  truth,  there  is  the  very  noble 
sentiment  with  which  M.  Poincare  begins  his  book  La  valeur  de  la 
science :  "The  search  for  truth  ought  to  be  the  aim  of  our  activity ; 
it  is  the  only  end  which  is  worthy  of  it."  Very  nice,  but  with 
regard  to  what  the  French  call  "logistics"  or  "mathematical  logic," 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  483 

and  everybody  used  to  call  "symbolic  logic,"  M.  Poincare  has  not 
been  as  true  to  his  lofty  sentiment  as  his  admirers  have  learned  to 
expect  and  demand. 

Under  these  circumstances  it  seems  only  fair — I  do  not  mean 
to  logistics  but  to  the  public — to  give  people  the  opportunity  to 
read  M.  Couturat's  answer  as  well  as  M.  Poincare's  attack. 

In  the  following  translation,  any  bibliographical  or  other  notes 
which  I  have  added  are  enclosed  in  square  brackets.  Where  possible 
I  have  abbreviated  the  translation  and  avoided  the  use  of  symbols. 

There  are  a  few  passages  in  M.  Couturat's  article  which  may 
possibly  give  rise  to  a  wrong  impression.  Thus,  he  speaks  of  logical 
demonstrations  making  true  the  chance  finds  of  the  intellect.  Of 
course  the  process  of  demonstration  does  not  do  this:  It  gives  the 
finder  and  other  people  certainty  as  to  whether  the  find  is  true  or 
not.  But  we  must  not  accuse  M.  Couturat  of  being  a  pragmatist  on 
the  slender  grounds  of  a  loosely  expressed  sentence ;  especially  as  in 
other  parts  of  this  article  he  has  protested  in  the  clearest  possible 
way  against  the  confusion  between  creation  and  discovery. 

Near  the  end  of  the  second  section  there  is  a  reference  to  a 
number  of  mathematicians  who  failed  adequately  to  deal  with  the 
paradox  discovered  by  Burali-Forti,  among  whom  are  mentioned 
Russell  and  myself.  The  article  of  Russell  referred  to  contains, 
implicitly,  a  criticism  of  certain  views  widely  held  by  mathematicians 
at  that  time  and  also — again  implicitly — the  solution  of  the  paradox 
and  others  like  it.  This  of  course  was  familiar  to  M.  Couturat,  but 
the  citation  of  Russell  in  that  connection  might  mislead  some  people. 
With  regard  to  myself,  at  the  time  (1903-1904)  that  I  wrote  the 
papers  referred  to  I  was  hardly,  as  M.  Couturat  says,  "totally  a 
stranger  to  logistics,"  but  I  freely  grant  that  I  was  not  as  familiar 
with  it  as  is  necessary  even  to  grasp  the  full  bearings  of  the  ques- 
tion. My  attempt  at  the  solution,  though  I  believe  it  has  one  small 
merit  in  distinguishing  between  what  may  be  called  entity  and 
existence,  I  have  since  then  abandoned. 

The  discussion,  in  the  third  of  M.  Couturat's  sections,  of  the 
question  of  existence  does  not  appear  to  me  to  be  satisfactory,  and 
I  have  added  a  note  referring  to  some  former  remarks  of  mine  on 
this  subject  in  The  Monist  for  January,  1910.  p.  E.  B.  j. 

REPLY  TO  M.   POINCARE. 

I  thank  M.  Poincare  for  the  honor  which  he  has  done 
me  by  taking  me  in  particular  as  the  subject  of  his  articles 


484  THE  MONIST. 

on  "Mathematics  and  Logic/'3  but  I  must  say  that  I  do  not 
deserve  this  honor,  for  the  ideas  which  I  have  presented  are 
not  my  own  and  I  fear  that  M.  Poincafe  has  done  them  a 
great  wrong  by  discussing  them  from  a  work  in  which  they 
are  given  at  second-hand.  In  fact,  as  I  have  been  care- 
ful to  warn  my  readers,  my  articles4  were  mainly  only 
an  account  of  Mr.  Russell's  book;  and  wherever  I  have 
been  led  to  add  an  analysis  of  the  works  of  other  logis- 
ticians  I  have  not  omitted  to  refer  to  them.  Now  it  is  not 
customary  to  criticize  works  of  this  class  from  a  simple 
analysis  of  them,  above  all  when  the  value  of  these  works 
consists  in  the  rigor  of  demonstrations,  and  these  demon- 
strations are  necessarily  absent  from  my  summary  exposi- 
tion. For  example,  I  have  analyzed  long  memoirs  of 
Peano,  Pieri  and  Whitehead  by  limiting  myself  to  the  enun- 
ciation of  their  chief  theorems,  without  the  quotation  of 
a  single  demonstration.  It  is  constantly  assumed  that  the 
reader  who  wishes  to  see  the  demonstration  of  such  and 
such  a  theorem  has  only  to  seek  out  the  original  memoirs, 
and  it  would  obviously  be  pointless  to  reproach  me  for  not 
having  given  it.  Similarly  I  have  thought  I  ought  to 
describe  in  my  book,  to  complete  one  of  my  articles, 
Peano's  space-filling  curve  in  an  elementary  and  intuitive 
form  which  is  accessible  to  the  first  comer  and  without 
speaking  of  the  rigid  analytical  demonstration.  What 
would  one  think  of  a  mathematician  who,  only  knowing 
this  curve  by  my  account  of  it,  allowed  himself  to  criticize 
its  construction,  to  doubt  the  rigor  of  the  demonstration, 
or  to  declare  that  this  demonstration  does  not  exist  and 
that  the  proposition  in  question  rests  on  intuition  ? 

Also  I  had  warned  my  readers  that  in  my  work  I  would 

*  [See  Dr.  G.  B.  Halsted's  translation  of  "The  New  Logics"  in  The  Monist 
of  April  1912,  and  of  "The  Latest  Efforts  of  the  Logisticians"  in  the  present 
number.] 

*  Published,  with  some  corrections  and  additions,  in  a  volume  bearing  the 
title,  Les  principes  des  mathematiques,  Paris,  Alcan,  1905. 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  485 

sacrifice  rigor  to  clearness,  not  to  that  logical  clearness 
which  is  inseparable  from  rigor  and  which  can  only  be 
obtained  by  logistical  symbolism,  but  to  that  clearness 
in  the  common  acceptation  of  the  term  which  is  called 
intuition  and  which  M.  Poincare  esteems  so  highly.  It 
must  be  granted  that  I  am  very  badly  rewarded  for  the 
concessions  which  I  have  made  to  intuition,  since  M.  Poin- 
care profits  by  them  to  reproach  me  with  a  lack  of  rigor. 
In  any  case,  I  wished  to  do  the  work  of  a  commentator  and 
a  popularizer  and  to  compose  for  the  use  of  the  laity  a  kind 
of  introduction  to  the  works  of  which  I  gave  a  short  ac- 
count. That  is  to  say,  it  was  not  for  M.  Poincare  that  I 
wrote,  and  I  did  not  pretend  to  teach  him  anything  about 
these  works.  In  all  cases,  a  work  of  the  kind  I  wrote  may 
serve — I  hope  so  at  least — to  teach  the  elements  of  the 
doctrines  in  question,  but  it  cannot  serve  as  a  sufficient 
basis  to  criticize  these  doctrines;  to  be  just  and  effective, 
the  criticism  ought  to  be  on  the  original  works  from  which 
I  drew  my  inspiration.  What  would  M.  Poincare  say  if 
some  one  took  it  upon  himself  to  discuss  Hilbert's  prin- 
ciples of  geometry5  from  the  analysis — however  exact  and 
complete  it  may  be — which  he  has  given  of  it  to  the  French 
public  ? 

I  might  stop  with  these  remarks,  and  perhaps  I  ought 
to  do  so ;  for  if  I  have  already  compromised  the  doctrines 
in  question  by  my  attempt  at  popularization,  I  run  the  risk 
of  compromising  them  still  more  by  undertaking  to  defend 
them  against  an  adversary  like  M.  Poincare.  If  I  have  re- 
solved so  to  defend  them,  it  is,  on  the  one  hand,  because  it 
has  pleased  M.  Poincare  to  substitute  me  for  the  masters 
of  logistics,  and,  on  the  other  hand,  because  these  masters 
have  believed  that  I  would  suffice  for  the  task  and  have 
left  to  me  the  care  of  justifying  them.  I  thank  them  for 

B  [The  Foundations  of  Geometry,  trans,  by  Townsend.  Chicago,  The  Open 
Court  Publishing  Co.] 


486  THE  MONIST 

their  confidence ;  but  the  reader  ought  to  know  that  if  there 
is  any  thing  good  and  enduring  in  my  work  it  is  to  those 
masters  that  I  owe  it,  and  that  all  that  is  feeble  and  defec- 
tive comes  from  myself.  If  then  I  succeed  in  justifying 
logistics  against  the  criticisms  of  M.  Poincare,  so  much  the 
better;  if  not,  it  will  be  my  fault  and  will  prove  nothing 
against  logistics. 

f  I. 

In  the  first  place,  we  must  not  confuse  logistics  with 
what  M.  Poincare  calls  "the  logic  of  M.  Hilbert."  M.  Pom- 
care  has  not  made  this  confusion,  but  many  of  his  readers 
may  do  so  when  they  see  him  associate  these  two  doctrines 
in  the  same  discussion  and  in  a  common  condemnation. 
Now  it  must  be  clearly  realized  that  Hilbert  is  a  complete 
stranger  to  logistics  and  has  never  used  any  logical  cal- 
culus in  his  researches.  If  then  the  criticisms  that  M.  Poin- 
care makes  against  him  are  just,  they  have  no  bearing 
against  logistics,  but  rather  tend  to  prove  the  superiority 
of  logistics  over  verbal  reasoning  and  simple  common  sense. 

It  is  important  also  to  correct  a  historical  error  to 
which  the  following  phrase  of  M.  Poincare  may  give  rise: 
"What  Hilbert  has  done  for  geometry  others  wish  to  do 
for  arithmetic  and  analysis."  We  might  believe  from  this 
passage  that  the  logisticians  attack  the  subject  of  arith- 
metic and  analysis  after  the  works  of  Hilbert  on  geometry, 
and  in  imitation  of  them.  The  Grundlagen  der  Geometric6 
of  Hilbert  were  published  in  1899.  Now,  ten  years  before 
this  (in  1889)  Peano  had  published  not  only  his  Arith 
metices  principia  nova  methodo  exposita  but  also  /  Prin- 
cipii  di  Geometria  logicamente  esposti,  both  of  which  were 
written  in  the  symbolism  which  he  had  invented  in  the  year 
before.  In  1891  he  published  in  the  first  volume  of  the 
Rivista  di  Matematica  two  articles  on  the  concept  of  num- 

6  [English  translation  as  noted  above.] 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  487 

her  which  already  contained  the  five  fundamental  axioms 
of  arithmetic.  In  1894  he  published  in  the  fourth  volume 
of  the  same  Rivista  the  memoir  on  the  foundations  of  ge- 
ometry which  I  have  analyzed  in  Les  Principes  des  Mathe- 
matiques.7  Lastly,  in  1899  Fieri  published  his  logical  re- 
construction of  projective  geometry  and  of  metrical  geom- 
etry in  the  Memoirs  of  the  Turin  Academy.  These  dates 
are  enough  to  prove  that,  if  Hilbert  has  not  wished  to 
profit  by  the  works  of  the  logisticians,  the  logisticians 
could  not  have  profited  by  his  work  and  had  no  need  of  his 
example  not  only  in  arithmetic  and  analysis  but  even  in 
geometry.  Consequently  M.  Poincare  commits  a  histor- 
ical error  in  attributing  to  the  "works  of  M.  Hilbert" 
the  "triumph"  of  logistics  in  geometry.  I  content  my- 
self, on  this  point,  with  stating  a  fact:  In  1900  Hilbert 
elaborated  for  arithmetic  a  complicated  system  of  eighteen 
axioms,8  when  eleven  years  before  this  arithmetic  had  been 
built  up  on  five  axioms  only,  which  Padoa  in  1902  reduced 
to  four.  Finally,  to  render  to  each  person  the  "chrono- 
logical" justice  which  is  due  to  him,  I  should  record  that 
Frege  stated,  in  his  Grundlagen  der  Arithmetik  of  1884, 
the  theory  of  the  integer  number  which  Russell  has  adopted 
in  principle,  and  undertook  to  prove  that  the  principles  of 
arithmetic  are  purely  logical — analytical  in  Kant's  sense. 
M.  Poincare  writes :  "This  invention  of  M.  Peano  was 
called  pasigraphy,"  and  adds :  "This  name  exactly  defines 
its  bearing."  The  first  phrase  contains  an  error  of  fact. 
Never  did  Peano  call  his  logical  symbolism  by  the  name  of 
"pasigraphy";  he  always  called  it  "mathematical  logic".9 
If  I  call  it  "logistics,"  it  is  first,  because  of  the  equivocal- 

T  Chap.  VI,  pp.  159-180. 

8  "Ueber  den  Zahlbegriff,"  Jahresber.  der  deutsch.  Math.-Ver.,  Vol.  VIII, 
1900.  [This  essay  was  reprinted  in  an  appendix  to  the  3d  German  edition  of 
the  Grundlagen  der  Geometric,  Leipsic  and  Berlin,  1909,  pp.  256-262.] 

8  See  all  the  editions  of  Peano' s  Formulaire  de  Mathematiques,  and  the 
Notations  de  Logique  mathematique  (Turin,  1894)  which  forms  the  introduc- 
tion to  the  first  edition. 


488  THE  MONIST. 

ness  of  the  expression  "mathematical  logic,"  and,  secondly, 
not  because  "this  new  name  implies  the  purpose  of  revo- 
lutionizing logic,"  but  because  this  good  old  word,  which 
Vieta  gave  to  algebra,  indicates,  by  its  very  etymology, 
the  general  art  of  reasoning  and  calculating.  In  this  sense 
it  was  employed  in  the  eighteenth  century  by  Lambert  to 
denote  his  own  logical  calculus.10  It  was  Schroder  who 
first  called  it  "pasigraphy"  in  a  communication  made  to  the 
first  congress  of  mathematicians  at  Zurich  in  1898,  and 
that  probably  with  a  depreciative  intention."  Now  this 
word  is  quite  inexact,  whatever  M.  Poincare  may  say. 
People  call  any  written  universal  language  a  "pasigraphy" ; 
thus  the  international  code  of  maritime  signals12  is  a 
"pasigraphy."  I  myself  formerly  used  this  word  when 
speaking  of  Peano's  symbolism  but  I  corrected  it  at  once : 
"A  system  of  pasigraphy  or,  better,  of  ideography"  ;13  this 
means  that  the  symbols  translate  not  words  or  phrases  but 
ideas.  I  concluded  the  same  article  by  the  words:  "We 
would  restrict  incorrectly  the  value  of  Peano's  symbolism 
if  we  only  regarded  it  as  a  kind  of  stenography.  It  is 
also  and  chiefly  an  instrument  of  logical  analysis,  of  deduc- 
tion and  of  verification" ;  and  I  recalled,  a  propos  of  this, 
the  "universal  characteristic"  of  Leibniz.  It  is,  then,  en- 
tirely to  misinterpret  the  nature  and  bearing  of  logistics 
to  regard  it  as  a  mere  pasigraphy. 

For  the  rest,  M.  Poincare  speaks  of  logistics  in  the 
way  in  which  a  bel  esprit  might  speak  of  algebra  or  mathe- 
matics in  general.  For  example,  he  says:  "The  essential 
elements  of  this  language  are  certain  algebraic  signs  which 
represent  the  different  conjunctions  if,  and,  or,  and  then. 
That  these  signs  may  be  convenient  is  possible,  but  that 

10"Versuch  einer  Zeichenkunst  in  der  Vernunftlehre,  Logische  und  philo- 
sophische  Abhandlungen,  edited  by  John  Bernoulli,  Berlin,  1782. 

11  Translated  into  English  in  The  Monist  for  October,  1898. 

13  Cf.  Couturat  and  Leau,  Histoire  de  la  langue  universelle  (Paris,  1903), 
preliminary  chapter  on  "Les  pasigraphies." 

18  Bulletin  des  Sciences  mathematiques,  Vol.  XXV,  1901. 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  489 

they  are  destined  to  revolutionize  the  whole  philosophy  is 
another  question.  It  is  difficult  to  admit  that  the  word  if 
acquires,  when  it  is  written  D,  a  virtue  which  it  did  not 
have  when  it  was  written  if."  In  the  first  place  we  must 
not  believe  that  logistical  symbols  are  limited  to  the  literal 
translation  of  some  words.14  The  sign  D  translates  if  no 
more  than  then,  it  expresses  the  idea  of  implication;  the 
same  sign  may  translate  and  in  certain  cases  and  or  in 
other  cases.  Inversely,  the  word  and  has  not  the  same 
meaning  in  the  three  following  cases:  "Peter  is  rich  and 
happy,"  "Peter  and  Paul  are  rich,"  "Peter  and  Paul  are 
brothers" ;  and  consequently  it  is  not  translated  by  the  same 
logistical  symbol.  It  is,  then,  quite  unjust  to  consider  "the 
new  language"  as  a  mere  tracing  of  ordinary  language  and 
consequently  as  having  no  value  and  no  utility  of  its  own/5 
M.  Poincare  believes  that  I  attach  "an  exaggerated  im- 
portance which  would  astonish  M.  Peano  himself"  to  the 
use  of  symbols.  I  can  reassure  him  on  this  point.  M. 
Peano  writes  to  me  on  this  subject :  "I  have  always  affirmed 
the  importance  of  symbolic  notation  in  all  mathematical 
propositions,  its  great  utility  in  difficult  and  delicate  ques- 
tions, and  its  indispensability  in  the  study  of  principles. 
That  is  written  down  in  all  the  volumes  of  the  Formulaire 
.  . .  ."Everywhere  and  always  he  insists  upon  the  necessity 
of  expressing  every  mathematical  proposition  and  every 
definition  entirely  in  symbols.16 

"Like  the  childish  notations  of  Herigone,  who  wrote,  for  example,  "5<" 
for  pentagon ;  or  like  any  system  of  analogous  abbreviations  that  a  mathematical 
student  may  invent  for  taking  notes. 

"In  1895  Peano  wrote:  "Mathematical  logic does  not  reduce  merely 

to  an  abbreviated  symbolical  writing,  to  a  kind  of  tachygraphy;  it  allows  us 
to  study  the  laws  of  these  signs  and  the  transformations  of  propositions. . . . 
The  two  objects  of  mathematical  logic,  the  formation  of  a  symbolical  script 
and  the  study  of  the  forms  of  transformations  (or  of  reasoning)  are  closely 
connected"  ("Sur  la  definition  de  la  limite  d'une  fonction,"  American  Journal 
of  Mathematics,  Vol.  XVII).  This  memoir  was  meant  (as  its  subtitle  "Exer- 
cice  de  logique  mathematique"  shows)  to  make  the  new  logic  known  to  mathe- 
maticians. Mathematicians  then  cannot  be  excused  for  still  ignoring  it,  and 
it  is  doubly  inexcusable  for  them  to  criticize  it  without  knowing  it. 

18  Cf.  his  memoir  printed  at  Paris  in  1900  among  those  read  at  the  first 
international  congress  of  philosophy. 


49O  THE  MONIST. 

However  that  may  be,  there  was  some  one  who  had  an 
opinion  which  is  as  "exaggerated"  as  that  of  Peano  and 
myself  of  the  importance  of  symbolism,  and  that  was  Leib- 
niz. He  went  as  far  as  to  say  that  the  discoveries  in  mathe- 
matics that  he  had  made  arose  solely  from  the  fact  that  he 
had  perfected  the  use  of  symbols,  and  his  discovery  of  the 
infinitesimal  calculus  was,  for  him,  only  a  specimen  of  his 
char  act  eristic  a  universalis.17  In  fact,  we  know  that  he  did 
not  invent  infinitesimal  ideas ;  he  only  invented  a  symbolism 
to  represent  them  and  an  algorithm  to  manipulate  them. 
We  might  say  of  him :  "He  only  introduced  two  new  signs, 
d  and  /.  That  these  signs  may  be  convenient  is  possible; 
that  they  could  revolutionize  the  whole  of  mathematics  is 
incredible."  We  might  also  say  of  algebra:  "It  consists 
simply  in  representing  by  signs  the  words  plus,  minus, 
multiplied  by,  and  divided  by.  But  it  is  not  to  be  seen 
how  it  constitutes  a  progress  beyond  arithmetic ;  it  is  diffi- 
cult to  admit  that  the  word  plus  when  it  is  written  +  ac- 
quires a  virtue  that  it  did  not  possess  when  written  plus." 
And  yet,  could  the  theory  of  equations  and  the  theory  of 
algebraic  forms  have  been  elaborated  with  words? 

M.  Poincare  asserts  that  "pasigraphy  does  not  preserve 
us  from  error."  Without  doubt  it  does  not,  any  more  than 
the  rules  of  algebra  or  arithmetic  do.  Does  it  follow  that 
these  rules  are  false  or  that  we  ought  to  defy  them?  Be- 
cause we  make  mistakes  in  addition,  must  we  condemn  the 
four  rules  of  arithmetic  and  even  the  arithmetical  signs, 
and  only  count  on  our  fingers  or  with  little  balls  ?  The  mis- 
takes which  a  logistician  may  commit  do  not  weaken  the 
value  of  logistics  any  more  than  mistakes  in  calculation 
shatter  the  certainty  of  arithmetic.  It  is  enough  that 
logistics  allows  us  to  reason  more  easily  and  more  surely 
and  to  discover  faults  of  reasoning  more  easily;  and  that 

17  See  Couturat,  La  Logique  de  Leibniz,  pp.  84-85,  the  texts  cited  in  the  note 
and  the  third  appendix. 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  49 1 

is  what  it  does.  In  this  sense  it  is,  as  Leibniz  said,  an  art 
of  infallibility — not  that  logisticians  are  infallible,  but  they 
are  less  exposed  to  error  than  those  who  trust  to  simple 
common  sense,  that  is  to  say  to  intuition. 

Besides,  M.  Poincare  forms  quite  a  false  idea  of  logis- 
tics by  considering  it  as  a  mechanism  from  which  intelli- 
gence is  nearly  excluded ;  and  his  comparison  of  it  with  the 
"logical  piano"  of  Stanley  Jevons  is  not  exact.  We  must 
first  of  all  know  that  this  logical  piano  merely  concerns 
logical  classes  and  that  it  only  effects  the  least  important 
— and  the  most  mechanical — part  of  reasoning.  Its  office 
consists  in  suppressing  the  elementary  classes  which  are 
annulled  in  virtue  of  the  given  premises.  But  it  leaves 
almost  all  the  rest  to  be  done;  thus,  on  the  one  hand,  we 
have  to  put  the  logical  problem  into  equations,  and,  on  the 
other  hand,  we  have  to  combine  the  subsisting  classes  in 
such  a  way  as  to  obtain  the  consequences  in  the  desired 
form.  Thus  the  algebra  of  logic  does  not  reduce  to  a  blind 
mechanism.  This  is  still  more  true  of  logistics  which  sur- 
passes the  algebra  of  logic  and  is  much  less  "mechanical." 

Another  comparison  is  no  happier:  "Are  the  rules  of 
perfect  logic  the  whole  of  mathematics  ?  We  might  just  as 
well  say  that  the  whole  art  of  the  player  of  chess  reduces  to 
the  rules  for  moving  the  pieces."  But  nobody  ever  asserted 
that  all  mathematics  reduces  materially  to  logic,  that  is  to 
say  that  there  is  nothing  more  in  a  treatise  on  mathematics 
than  in  a  treatise  on  logic.  We  maintain  only  that  all 
mathematical  reasonings  are  effected  in  virtue  of  the  rules 
of  logic  alone,  in  the  same  way  that  all  the  games  of  chess 
that  have  been  and  can  be  played  are  effected  according  to 
the  rules  of  the  game .  . .  . ,  otherwise  the  rules  would  be 
worthless.  The  comparison  returns  then  against  the  ad- 
versaries of  logistics,  for  it  shows  how  a  small  number  of 
elements,  combined  according  to  some  few  fixed  laws,  can 
generate  an  unlimited  variety  of  consequences.  People 


492  THE  MONIST. 

have  asserted  that  logistics  put  leading-strings  on  inven- 
tion, and  have  urged  against  logistics  the  rights  of  genius. 
How  could  mathematics  constantly  evolve  and  progress  if 
it  is  always  condemned  to  rest  on  a  small  number  of  prin- 
ciples and  "logical  constants"  ?  M.  Poincare  does  not  use 
this  argument  and  leaves  on  one  side  the  question  of  in- 
vention ;  but  it  is  clearly  visible  that  the  theory  of  "logical 
constants"  inspires  in  him  an  instinctive  repugnance,  and 
that  every  attempt  to  catalogue  the  primitive  notions  and 
principles  of  mathematics  appears  to  him  to  be  an  insup- 
portable pretension  and  a  restriction  on  the  "liberty"  of  the 
scientific  man.  It  is  for  that  reason  that  he  opposes  to 
logical  and  demonstrative  reason  the  "sure  instinct"  of  the 
inventor  and  the  "more  profound  geometry"  which  guides 
him;  and  these  kinds  of  considerations  are  very  much  in 
fashion.  It  is,  at  the  present  time,  fashionable  to  put  the 
"logic  of  nature  and  of  life"  in  opposition  to  formal  logic 
that  is  disdainfully  called  "dialectical,"  "abstract,"  and 
"verbal." 

There  is  here  a  confusion  which  it  is  important  to  dissi- 
pate. To  oppose  to  logic  the  psychological  fact  of  invention 
is  to  commit  the  most  gross  ignoratio  elenchi,  Logic  has 
neither  to  inspire  invention  nor  to  explain  it;  it  contents 
itself  with  controlling  it  and  verifying  it  in  the  proper  sense 
of  the  word  (making  it  true).  Do  we  reproach  metrical 
science  for  not  giving  poetical  genius  or  the  science  of  har- 
mony for  not  conferring  musical  genius?  And  do  we 
therefore  conclude  that  the  rules  of  both  have  no  value 
and  no  utility?  As  for  the  theory  of  "logical  constants," 
the  liberty  of  the  mathematical  discoverer  is  no  more  re- 
stricted by  formulating  the  primitive  principles  and  notions 
on  which  his  science  rests  than  the  libetry  of  the  musician, 
of  the  painter  and  of  the  poet  is  restricted  by  saying  to 
them  in  turn:  "As  for  you,  you  will  never  be  able  to  do 
anything  but  combine  the  seven  fundamental  notes  with 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  493 

their  accidentals;  as  for  you,  the  seven  colors  of  the  spec- 
trum, and  as  for  you,  the  twenty-six  letters  of  the  alpha- 
bet." That  is  exactly  in  what  measure  logistics  clogs  in- 
vention and  clips  the  wings  of  genius.  People  should  really 
stop  throwing  invention  at  the  head  of  logicians,  as  if 
invention  could  be  contrary  to  logic.  Besides,  this  "sure 
instinct"  and  this  "more  profound  geometry"  which  guide 
the  discoverer  are  only  unconscious  forms  of  the  logical 
reason  and  proceed  according  to  the  same  laws.  The  rea- 
son which  invents  is  conformable,  and  at  bottom  iden- 
tical, with  the  reason  which  demonstrates,  and  without 
it  the  latter  could  not  verify  what  the  former  has  by 
chance  found;  and  these  chance  finds  are  only  true  on  this 
condition.  It  is,  then,  conformity  with  the  laws  of  logic 
"which  alone  gives  value  to  the  edifice  which  has  been 
built." 

M.  Poincare  speaks  of  "the  logic  of  Russell"  and  op- 
poses it  to  the  logic  of  Aristotle,  as  if  Mr.  Russell  was  the 
first  to  go  beyond  the  confines  of  the  Aristotelian  logic. 
He  appears  besides  to  have  an  inexact  notion  of  the  Aristo- 
telian logic  when  he  says:  "The  logic  of  propositions  of 
Russell  is  the  study  of  the  laws  according  to  which  the 
conjunctions  if,  and,  or  and  the  negation  not  are  combined. 
It  is  a  considerable  extension  of  the  ancient  logic."  I  can 
assure  M.  Poincare  that  Aristotle  was  already  acquainted 
with  the  conjunctions  if,  and,  or  and  negation,  and  that  he 
took  account  of  them  in  his  logic.  All  the  classical  logicians 
knew  and  studied  hypothetical  judgments  (where  if  fig- 
ures), copulative  judgments  (where  and  figures),  and 
disjunctive  judgments  (where  or  figures) ;  and  classical 
logic  has  always  admitted  negative  judgments.  If  M.  Poin- 
care means  that  Mr.  Russell  is  the  first  who  has  translated 
these  judgments  into  symbols  and  submitted  them  to  an 
algorithm  he  is  at  least  half  a  century  out  of  his  reckoning : 
for  it  is  to  Boole  (without  speaking  of  his  fore-runners) 


494  THE  MONIST. 

that  this  honor  is  due.  It  is,  then,  not  Mr.  Russell  who  has 
"adjoined"  to  syllogistics  "the  conjunctions  and  and  or" 
and  who  has  thus  "opened  up  a  new  domain  to  logic." 

M.  Poincare  believes  that  he  can  establish  a  funda- 
mental difference  between  the  two  logics  by  remarking  that 
"the  symbols  are  multiplied  and  permit  of  varied  combina- 
tions which  are  no  longer  Unite  in  number"  and  he  adds : 
"Have  we  any  right  to  give  this  extension  to  the  meaning 
of  the  word  logic?"  It  would,  then,  seem  that  for  him 
logic  is  characterized  by  the  limited  number  of  the  com- 
binations which  it  admits.  But  I  do  not  see  that  there  is  a 
radical  difference.  Besides,  in  what  sense  did  the  ancient 
logic  only  admit  a  limited  number  of  combinations?  Is  it 
a  question  of  the  number  of  valid  moods  of  the  syllogism? 
But  modern  logic,  too,  only  admits  a  limited  number  of 
simple  types  of  reasoning.  Is  it  a  question,  on  the  other 
hand,  of  the  infinite  diversity  of  complex  reasonings  that 
one  can  obtain  by  combining  these  types?  But  classical 
logic  too  could  form  an  infinity  of  reasonings  by  combining 
syllogisms.  In  all  cases  the  two  logics  have  the  same  char- 
acter and  only  differ  in  respect  of  the  more  or  less.  Be- 
sides, how  is  the  number  relevant  in  this  matter?  If  a 
logical  principle  is  true,  whether  it  be  the  principle  of  the 
syllogism  or  any  other,  is  it  not  capable  of  justifying  an 
infinite  number  of  reasonings  just  as  well  as  a  finite  num- 
ber? Does  its  demonstrative  virtue  by  some  chance  be- 
come exhausted  after  n  applications  ?  Lastly,  what  means 
this  reproach  addressed  to  logistics  of  admitting  an  in- 
finite number  of  combinations,  when,  on  the  other  hand, 
it  is  reproached  with  only  having  a  very  limited  number  of 
principles?  Is  it  not,  rather,  for  it,  just  as  it  is  for  geom- 
etry (according  to  a  well-known  phrase),  a  glory  to  deduce 
from  so  small  a  number  of  principles  so  great  a  number  of 
consequences  ?  How  can  this  fact  scandalize  a  mathemati- 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  495 

cian  who  is  familiar  with  the  incredible  fruitfulness  of  the 
theory  of  combinations? 

When  M.  Poincare  opposes  the  old  and  the  new  logic 
to  one  another  and  considers  the  latter  as  an  enormous  and 
perhaps  illegitimate  "extension"  of  the  former,  he  appears 
to  forget  the  fact  that  the  domain  of  a  science  may  receive 
an  extension — even  a  considerable  one — without  the  notion 
and  the  definition  of  this  science  changing.  Otherwise  we 
could  never  speak  of  the  progress  of  the  sciences :  M.  Poin- 
care seems  to  suppose  by  that  that  a  science  remains  in 
essentials  identical  with  itself  in  the  course  of  its  historical 
development.  The  reasoning  of  M.  Poincare  would  serve 
to  prove  that  the  infinitesimal  calculus  is  not  a  part  of 
mathematics ;  that  electricity  is  not  relevant  to  physics,  and 
that  the  theory  of  organic  compounds  is  not  relevant  to 
chemistry.  Now  it  is  for  this  reason  that  the  extension 
of  the  "field"  of  classical  logic  becomes  an  extension  of 
the  "meaning  of  the  word  logic"  M.  Poincare  says  again : 
"It  seems  that  there  is  nothing  new  to  write  about  formal 
logic  and  that  Aristotle  saw  to  the  bottom  of  it."  If  he 
means  by  that  (as  Kant  did)  that  logic  has  made  no  prog- 
ress since  Aristotle,  it  is  nowadays  a  simple  error  of  fact; 
but  if  he  means  that  logic  ought  to  remain  (or  ought  to 
have  remained)  confined  in  the  domain  assigned  to  it  by 
Aristotle,  he  maintains  implicitly  that  logic  was  perfect 
and  complete  at  its  birth,  and  this  is  contrary  to  the  analogy 
of  all  the  other  sciences  and  to  probability.  We  would 
only  smile  at  a  man  who  claimed  to  reduce  mathematics  to 
what  it  was  in  the  time  of  Euclid,  and  physics  to  Aristotle's 
physics.  How  then  dare  any  one  maintain  or  insinuate 
that  Aristotle  has  said  the  last  word  about  logic  and  that 
it  is  forbidden  to  develop  this  science  beyond  the  narrow 
limits  assigned  to  it  by  its  founder  ? 

Besides,  if  "the  new  logic  is  richer  than  the  classical 
logic,"  it  is  not  so  much  by  the  extension  of  its  domain  as 


496  THE  MONIST. 

by  the  deep  study  of  the  principles  that  have  always  di- 
rected those  reasonings  which  have  been  recognized  as  just 
by  that  rational  instinct  to  which  M.  Poincare  attaches  so 
much  value.  He  seems  to  reproach  the  logisticians  with 
"introducing"  into  logic  indefinable  notions  and  indemon- 
strable principles.  It  would  be  more  just  to  say  that  they 
have  discovered  or  recognized  them;  just  as  Aristotle  did 
not  invent  but  discovered  and  recognized  the  principle  of 
the  syllogism.  M.  Poincare  is  in  too  great  a  hurry  to  assert 
that  these  indemonstrable  principles  "are  appeals  to  intui- 
tion, are  synthetic  a  priori  judgments."  Perhaps  he  would 
have  been  of  another  opinion  if  he  had  taken  the  trouble 
to  run  through  the  enumeration  of  these  principles.  Why 
should  the  principle  of  composition:  "If  a  is  b,  and  a  is  c, 
then  a  is  be"  constitute  an  appeal  to  intuition  rather  than 
the  principle  of  the  syllogism:  "If  a  is  b,  and  b  is  c,  then 
a  is  c"  ?  In  what  is  the  principle  of  simplification :  "ab  is  a" 
more  synthetic  than  the  principle  of  identity  with  which  it 
has  been  so  often  confused  ?  In  any  case,  it  has  been  con- 
sidered by  Kant  as  the  type  of  analytic  judgments.  Is  it  of 
these  principles  that  M.  Poincare  said:  "We  regarded  them 
as  intuitive  when  we  met  them,  more  or  less  explicitly 
enunciated,  in  treatises  on  mathematics.  Have  they  changed 
character  because  the  meaning  of  the  word  logic  is  en- 
larged and  we  now  find  them  in  a  book  called  Treatise  on 
Logic"  ?  In  what  treatise  of  mathematics  has  M.  Poincare 
seen  them  formulated?  And  his  argument  returns  on  him- 
self, for  even  if  they  were  put  in  a  treatise  on  mathematics, 
would  that  change  their  character  as  logical  principles? 
"They  have  not  changed  their  nature,  they  have  only 
changed  place"  writes  M.  Poincare  in  italics ;  but  it  is  he 
who  has  changed  place.  It  is  not  enough  that  they  should 
be  used  in  mathematical  reasonings  to  call  them  mathe- 
matical, and  it  is  not  enough  that  they  are  not  found  in 
treatises  on  classical  logic  to  refuse  to  them  the  title  of 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  497 

logical  principles.  Otherwise  it  would  be  necessary  to  say 
that  logical  principles  are,  by  definition,  those  which  Aris- 
totle and  the  schoolmen  have  discovered  and  formulated; 
and  that  all  the  logical  principles  discovered  by  modern 
logicians  are  intuitive.  The  distinction  of  the  logical  and 
the  intuitive  would  then  reduce  to  a  question  of  chronology. 

Besides,  the  vague  conception  of  intuition  is  out  of 
place  as  a  weapon  against  the  logicians,  especially  when 
the  intuition  spoken  of  is  not  specified.  Is  intellectual  in- 
tuition meant,  which  bears  upon  the  relations  of  ideas,  or 
sensible  intuition,  which  necessarily  clothes  the  spatial 
form?  These  two  intuitions  are  wholly  different.  All 
logicians  are  ready  to  recognize  that  their  principles  pro- 
ceed from  intellectual  intuition,  that  is  to  say  they  are 
objects  of  immediate  knowledge  by  the  reason;  but  very 
few  will  agree  that  they  proceed  from  sensible  intuition, 
and  rest,  for  example,  as  Lange  has  maintained,  on  spatial 
schemata.  For  the  rest,  whatever  the  solution  of  this 
"metalogical"  problem  may  be,  all  the  logical  principles 
ought  to  have  the  same  fate ;  and  the  traditional  principles 
of  identity,  contradiction  and  so  on  will  be  "appeals  to 
intuition"  in  the  same  sense  and  in  the  same  measure  as 
the  others.  The  logisticians  then,  must  not  be  accused 
of  altering  logic  by  introducing  intuition  into  it ;  for  if  this 
accusation  has  any  value,  it  is  Aristotle  who  began  this 
introduction. 

In  any  case  it  is  inexact  to  say  that  "living"  reasonings, 
the  only  ones  "in  which  our  mind  remains  active,"  are 
"those  in  which  intuition  still  plays  a  part."  Purely  logical 
reasonings  need  more  mental  effort  and  ingenuity  than 
M.  Poincare  believes,  and,  even  with  the  mediocre  aid  of 
Jevon's  logical  piano,  a  certain  cleverness  is  necessary  to 
combine  the  brute  results  of  mechanism  and  to  draw  the 
conclusion  wished.  Besides,  why  reproach  logistics  with 


498  THE  MONIST. 

making  reasonings  easier  and  more  sure?18  If,  like  algebra, 
it  condenses  into  short  formulae  the  result  of  long  and 
complicated  reasonings,  it  is  to  relieve  the  powers  of  the 
mind  and  to  allow  it  to  embrace  a  greater  number  of  data 
and  to  draw  vaster  and  more  distant  conclusions.  Con- 
sequently, far  from  paralyzing  the  faculty  of  invention  or 
rendering  it  useless  logistics  lends  it  stilts  or  wings.  The 
discovering  mind  will  always  find  something  to  exercise 
itself  upon,  but  it  will  do  so  on  data  which  are  more  and 
more  complex.  That  is  what  happens  in  analysis,  where 
each  new  theory  combines  formulae  which  sum  up  the  re- 
sults of  simpler  and  more  elementary  theories.  M.  Poin- 
care may  then  be  reassured:  logistics  does  not  exclude 
genius. 

M.  Poincare  makes  a  curious  reproach  to  logistics: 
"The  part  of  intelligence  is  restricted  to  choosing  among 
a  limited  arsenal  rules  posited  beforehand,  and  has  not 
the  right  to  invent  new  ones."  If  we  remark  that  the 
"rules"  are  none  other  than  the  principles  of  logistics,  this 
phrase  appears  to  me  to  mean  that  intelligence  "has  the 
right"  to  invent  new  logical  principles.  It  is  a  strange 
conception  of  logic  to  consider  it  as  always  evolving  and 
as  never  finished.19  It  evidently  proceeds  from  the  psycho- 
logical confusion  between  the  science  and  what  we  know 
of  it  at  a  given  moment.  No  one  will  ever  "invent"  new 
rules  of  logic;  some  of  these  rules  which  had  not  been 
noticed  but  were  quite  as  "ancient"  as  the  others  and 
equally  "posited"  beforehand,  that  is  to  say  a  priori,  will 
perhaps  be  "discovered."  And  the  logisticians  do  not  do 
anything  else.  But  then,  why  does  M.  Poincare  reproach 

""More  sure,"  for  M.  Poincare  confesses  that  in  living  reasonings  "it  is 
difficult  not  to  introduce  an  axiom  or  postulate  which  is  unperceived."  Must 
we  conclude  from  that  that  "life"  is  incompatible  with  logic  ? 

19  To  use  the  favorite  comparison  of  M.  Poincare,  what  would  we  say  of 
a  chess-player  who  wished  to  invent  a  new  rule  in  the  middle  of  a  game, — 
for  example,  to  make  his  king  move  several  squares  when  in  check?  Such  an 
"invention"  would  be  called  trickery  and  nothing  else. 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  499 

them  with  innovating  ?  With  respect  to  the  nine  indefinable 
notions  and  the  twenty  indemonstrable  propositions  of  Rus- 
sell, he  says:  "I  believe  that.  . .  .1  would  have  found  some 
more."  He  is  quite  at  liberty  to  do  so:  the  logisticians  do 
not  ask  for  anything  better,  and  will  register  his  discoveries 
— or,  if  he  prefers  to  say,  his  inventions — with  gratitude. 
But  what  do  these  contradictory  reproaches  mean  if  not 
that  M.  Poincare  claims  for  himself  "the  right"  to  "invent" 
logical  principles  at  the  very  moment  when  he  refuses  this 
right  to  the  logisticians  ? 

For  the  rest,  what  good  is  it  to  discuss  in  abstracto  the 
qualities  of  logistics?  M.  Poincare  grants  that  "pasig- 
raphy  can  furnish  us  with  a  criterion  to  decide  the  question 
which  occupies  us.  If  every  treatise  on  mathematics  can 
be  translated  into  the  Peanian  language,  the  logisticians 
are  right."  Now  the  logisticians  replied  in  advance,  long 
ago,  to  this  ironical  invitation.  Ten  years  ago  Peano  pub- 
lished the  first  edition  of  his  Formulaire  de  Mathematiques, 
whicfc  is  precisely  a  treatise  or  manual  entirely  written  in 
logistics;  the  fourth  edition  (1903-1904)  comprises  Logic, 
Arithmetic,  Theory  of  Numbers,  Algebra,  the  Theory  of 
Real  Numbers,  the  Theory  of  Definite  Functions,  the  In- 
finitesimal Calculus,  the  Theory  of  Complex  Numbers,  the 
Theory  of  Circular  Functions,  the  Geometrical  Calculus 
(comprising  the  theory  of  vectors  and  the  theory  of  Qua- 
ternions), and  Differential  Geometry;  the  "Additions"  even 
contain  the  elements  of  kinematics.  The  fifth  edition  of 
the  Formulaire  is  in  course  of  publication.20  The  principal 
theorems  are  accompanied  by  their  logistical  demonstra- 
tions. I  will  add  that  this  mathematical  manual  is  a  collec- 
tive work  which  M.  Peano  and  his  collaborators  are  in- 
cessantly revising  and  perfecting. ,  Consequently  the  proof 

20  Professor  Peano  has  published,  besides,  a  classical  manual  entitled : 
Aritmetica  generate  e  algebra  elementare,  drawn  up  in  logistics  (Turin,  1902). 


5OO  THE  MONIST. 

which  M.  Poincare  requires  of  logisticians  was  given  long 
ago  and  is  being  completed  from  day  to  day. 

It  is  true  that  M.  Poincare  soon  seems  to  repent  of  his 
rash  concession  and  adds:  "Again  we  must  examine  the 
translation  closely.  It  is  not  sufficient  that  we  should  be 
presented  with  a  single  page  where  there  are  only  formulae 
and  not  a  single  word  of  ordinary  language,  in  order  that 
we  must  bow  down ....  It  will  be  necessary,  when  we  are 
in  the  presence  of  a  pasigraphical  reasoning,  even  when 
this  reasoning  is  correct,  to  examine  if  an  appeal  to  intui- 
tion is  not  hidden  away  in  some  corner."  These  reserves 
are  evidently  very  just  in  so  far  as  they  are  counsels  of 
critical  method.  But  why  does  M.  Poincare  not  conform 
to  them  ?  It  is  not  enough  to  express  these  general  reserves 
which  are  applicable  to  any  demonstrative  work,  to  weaken 
the  value  of  logistics  and  throw  disfavor  and  suspicion  on 
the  work  of  logisticians.  The  logisticians  have  given  to  the 
public  not  "one  page"  but  more  than  three  hundred  pages 
of  logistical  formulae  and  demonstrations.  Let  those  who 
have  doubts  on  the  value  of  these  demonstrations  "exam- 
ine" them  as  closely  as  they  wish  and  let  them  point  out 
lacunae  and  errors, — for  that  is  their  right  and  even  their 
duty.  But  the  burden  of  proof  falls  on  them,  and  it  is  not 
enough,  in  order  to  get  rid  of  this  burden,  to  shake  their 
heads  with  a  smile  of  incredulity. 

ii. 

I  pass  on  to  the  objections  aimed  at  logistics  in  so  far 
as  it  is  applied  to  mathematics.  Here  again  I  must  say 
that  M.  Poincare  wrongs  it  by  judging  it  merely  from  the 
"popular"  exposition  which  I  have  given  of  it.  In  effect, 
the  logistical  formulae  which  constitute,  as  M.  Poincare 
says,  a  "new  language"  are  sufficient  by  themselves  and  are 
intelligible  wholly  by  themselves;  if  it  were  necessary  to 
add  to  them  a  single  word  of  ordinary  language,  it  would 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  5OI 

prove  their  incompleteness  or  defectiveness.  Besides,  this 
"new  language"  was  invented  expressly  to  avoid  the  equiv- 
ocation or  the  beggings  of  the  question  implied  more  or  less 
confusedly  in  ordinary  language.  Consequently  the  logis- 
tical formulae  are  the  only  ones  which  can  be  exact,  rigor- 
ous and  exempt  from  the  above  logical  vices.  Thus,  when 
an  author  thinks  that  he  ought  to  translate  them  into  ordi- 
nary language,  it  is  merely  to  make  them  more  accessible 
to  the  "laity" ;  but  it  must  be  understood  that  this  verbal 
translation  is  always  imperfect,  approximate  and  by  no 
means  allows  the  proper  appreciation  of  the  logical  value 
of  the  formulae.  Just  because  language  cannot  equal 
the  precision  and  the  rigor  of  the  formulae,  I  have  made 
no  scruples  about  introducing  into  my  verbal  translations 
apparent  beggings  of  the  question  in  order  to  make  them 
more  clear  and  more  "French."  What  does  an  inexacti- 
tude more  or  less  matter  when  the  logistical  formula  alone 
counts  from  the  logical  point  of  view?  I  could  not  expect 
that  any  one  should  judge  and  condemn  these  formulae 
from  the  mere  inspection  of  the  verbal  translation  which  I 
gave  of  them  for  the  use  of  novices.  All  translation  is  a  be- 
trayal; but  that  is  still  more  true  when  the  translation 
makes  exactly  those  qualities  of  the  original  on  which  study 
and  discussion  bear  vanish.  It  is  exactly  as  if  some  one 
wished  to  study  the  meter  of  Virgil  in  a  French  trans- 
lation of  the  Aeneid. 

Now,  it  is  of  these  verbal  translations,  and  only  of  these 
verbal  translations,  that  M.  Poincare  has  taken  account  in 
his  criticism ;  he  does  not  appear  to  have  noticed  the  logis- 
tical formulae;  "It  is  Greek,  so  it  is  unread."  He  may 
then  "amuse  himself  by  counting  how  many  numerical  ad- 
jectives my  exposition  contains" :  that  will  prove  absolutely 
nothing  against  "pasigraphy."  Nevertheless  we  will  ex- 
amine his  arguments  one  by  one  in  order  to  show  better 
that  they  all  miss  the  point.  On  the  subject  of  the  logical 


5O2  THE  MONIST. 

definition  of  zero,  he  says:  "to  define  zero  by  something 
null  and  something  null  by  none  is  indeed  to  misuse  the 
richness  of  the  French  language."  Then  he  recognizes 
that  I  have  "introduced  an  improvement  in  my  definition" 
(a  double  inexactitude,  for  this  definition  is  not  my  own  and 
the  "improvement"  in  question  is  due  to  Mr.  Russell)  by 
writing  "what,"  according  to  M.  Poincare  "means,  in 
French,  zero  is  the  number  of  objects  which  satisfies  a  con- 
dition which  is  never  satisfied.  But  as  'never'  signifies  fin 
no  case9 1  do  not  see  that  the  progress  is  very  great."  I  will 
confine  myself  to  recalling  the  verbal  translation  that  I 
have  given  of  this  formula :  "if  qur  is  always  false,  A  is  the 
class  of  4r's  which  verify  qur."  The  verbal  translation  of 
that  is :  A  is  the  class  of  objects  which  satisfy  a  condition 
which  is  always  false,  that  is  to  say,  false  for  all  the  values 
attributed  to  x.  Where  is  to  be  seen  in  this  formula  the 
idea  of  the  number  zero  or  even  of  any  number  ?  And  are 
we  to  be  reproached  for  introducing  into  logic  mathe- 
matical notions,  when  classical  logic  was  acquainted  with 
universal  judgments  and  used  the  word  all?  To  be  able 
to  attribute  to  us  a  begging  of  the  question — even  one  that 
is  simply  verbal — M.  Poincare  has  had  to  transform  our 
translation  by  replacing  "always  false"  by  "never  true." 
If,  then,  somebody  here  abuses  the  French  language  it  is 
not  I. 

But  this  reproach  is  even  more  undeserved  if  it  is  ad- 
dressed to  the  logistician,  who  writes  neither  in  French 
nor  in  Italian  nor  in  English  but  in  a  symbolism  made  ex- 
pressly to  liberate  ideas  from  the  tacit  implications  that 
language  introduces  into  them  by  custom.  M.  Poincare 
himself  says :  "It  is  impossible  to  give  a  definition  without 
enunciating  a  phrase  and  difficult  to  enunciate  a  phrase 
without  putting  in  it  a  name  of  a  number  or  at  least  the 
word  many  or  a  word  in  the  plural.21  And  then  the  roof 

*  On  the  subject  of  the  plural,  it  may  be  remarked  that  Peano  has,  follow- 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  503 

is  slippery  and  at  every  moment  there  is  a  risk  of  falling 
into  a  begging  of  the  question."  These  very  just  reflections 
bear  only  on  the  logical  defects  of  language  and  on  the 
faults  that  language  can  make  us  commit.  It  is  precisely 
to  avoid  these  faults  and  to  cure  these  defects  that  the 
logisticians  have  invented  their  rigorously  defined  signs 
which  have  no  meaning  but  that  which  they  are  given  by 
definition.22  Put  shortly,  M.  Poincare's  argument  comes 
to  this :  "All  those  who  reason  with  the  words  of  ordinary 
language  are  liable  to  commit  beggings  of  the  question; 
now  the  logisticians  use,  not  words,  but  symbols  rigorously 
defined ;  consequently  they  too  must  commit  beggings  of  the 
question."  The  syllogism  is  not  conclusive  for  it  has  four 
terms.  And  even  if  it  had  only  three,  that  is  to  say  when 
one  could  legitimately  conclude  from  words  to  symbols, 
the  two  words  which  I  have  italicized  would  still  render  it 
invalid;  the  major  says  that  we  may  commit  errors;  the 
conclusion  asserts  that  certain  authors  have  necessarily 
committed  them. 

The  criticism  of  the  definition  of  the  number  i  is  no 
firmer.  "One  is  the  number  of  elements  of  a  class  of  which 
any  two  elements  are  identical";  such  is  the  verbal  trans- 
lation that  M.  Poincare  gives  of  this  definition.  "It  is 
more  satisfactory.  . .  .in  the  sense  that,  in  order  to  define 
i,  we  do  not  use  the  word  one] — but  still  the  word  two  is 
used" ;  and  M.  Poincare  rightly  suspects  that  two  can  only 
be  defined  by  means  of  one.23  But  he  makes  an  unjust  use 
of  the  fact  that  I  have  used  the  word  two  to  make  a  phrase 
in  ordinary  language.  The  more  exact  translation  of  the 
logistical  formula  is:  "i  is  the  class  of  classes  u  which  are 

ing  Leibniz's  recommendation,  excluded  it  from  the  "uninflected  Latin"  which 
he  has  given  out  as  a  form  of  international  language,  and  which  has  been 
adopted  by  many. 

22  Cf.  the  beginning  of  the  preface  to  Peano's  Arithmetices  principia  of 
1889. 

23  By  means  of  the  general  formula  by  which  we  define  n  + 1  by  means  of 
n;  cf.  Les  Principes  des  Mathematiques,  Chap.  II,  §  B,  p.  59. 


504  THE  MONIST. 

not  null  and  such  that  if  x  is  a  u  and  y  is  a  u  then  x  is 
identical  with  3;  whatever  x  and  y  may  be."  Where  is  there, 
I  do  not  say  the  word,  but  the  idea  of  two  in  this  formula  ? 
M.  Poincare  will  say  perhaps  that  two  (problematic)  ele- 
ments x  and  y  of  the  class  u  are  made  to  appear  in  it ;  but 
the  fact  that  they  are  two  does  not  come  into  the  question 
in  any  way;  and  the  proof  of  it  is  that  in  reality  they  are 
only  one:  x  and  y  are  merely  two  names  (excuse  me, 
names)  for  a  single  individual.  This  criticism  obviously 
has  no  bearing  on  another  equivalent  formula  which  I 
have  given,24  and  which  may  be  translated:  "One  is  the 
class  of  classes  u  which  are  not  null  and  such  that  if  x  is  a 
u  the  class  of  the  elements  of  u  which  are  not  identical  with 
x  is  null."  That  presupposes  of  course  the  definition  of  the 
null  class;  but,  as  we  see,  there  is  no  more  even  a  prob- 
lematical two  elements  of  u,  but  only  one,  and  we  only  ex- 
press that  there  is  no  other.25 

Will  anybody  say  that,  by  the  mere  fact  that  an  element 
is  spoken  of,  the  number  one  is  implied?26  But  that  is  an 
objection  which  M.  Poincare  does  not  formulate  and  to 
which  I  have  replied  in  advance  in  the  following  passage : 
"We  must  not  believe  that  the  definition  of  the  number 
one  constitutes  a  vicious  circle,  for  the  definition  of  the 
singular  class  rests  solely  on  the  relation  of  identity.  If 
it  is  true  that  it  implies  in  a  sense  the  unity  or  rather  the 
individuality  of  the  element  considered,  this  unity  cannot 
be  identical  with  the  number  one  which  is  to  be  defined :  for 
this  unity  is  a  property  of  each  element  while  the  number 
one  is  the  property  of  a  class ....  consequently,  in  all  cases 

24  Ibid.    I  have  logistically  deduced  this  from  the  preceding  one  on  p.  60. 

26  Here  is  a  more  fundamental  definition  that  Mr.  Russell  has  communi- 
cated to  me :  "One  is  the  class  of  classes  u  such  that  the  proposition :  'x  is  a  u' 
is  equivalent,  for  all  values  of  x,  to  (x  is  identical  with  c*  is  not  false  for  all 
values  of  c.' "  Notice  that  this  definition  does  not  presuppose  the  notion  of  the 
null  class.  As  for  the  formula  "x  is  a  u",  cf.  its  definition  farther  on. 

26  [In  French,  the  same  word  un  stands  for  both  an  and  one]. 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  505 

the  units  which  constitute  a  cardinal  number  are  different 
from  the  number  one."27 

The  confusion  which  exists  in  many  minds  between 
these  two  ideas  arises,  I  believe,  from  the  double  meaning 
of  the  word  for  one,  which  is  used  both  as  the  name  of  a 
number  and  as  an  indefinite  article.28  In  the  latter  case 
it  would  be  better  to  use  the  word  some  as  the  logicians 
do.29  This  equivocalness  exists  in  French  and  German, 
but  not  in  English.  If  then,  somebody  is  inclined  to  invoke 
it,  he  should  take  care  to  abuse  not  "the  richness"  but  the 
poverty  of  the  French  language.  To  sum  up,  it  is  not 
enough  to  conceive  any  one  object  to  conceive  the  number 
one,  nor  to  think  of  two  objects  together  to  have  by  that 
alone  the  idea  of  the  number  two.  From  the  fact  that  a 
logical  formula  contains  two  or  many  symbols  we  must 
not  conclude  that  it  implies  by  that  alone  the  idea  of  two 
or  of  some  other  number.  When  we  say:  "Peter  and  Paul 
are  wise,"  we  mean  to  say:  "Peter  is  wise  and  Paul  is 
wise";  we  do  not  think  the  number  two  and  we  have  no 
need  to  think  it  nor  to  notice  that  that  makes  "two  wise 
men."  In  the  same  way  when  we  say:  "#  and  y  are  ele- 
ments of  the  class  w,"3°  we  do  not  think  the  number  two 
and  no  idea  of  number  is  implied  in  this  proposition.31 

m  Les  Principes  dcs  Mathematiques,  Chap.  II,  §  A,  pp.  47-48.  M.  Pom- 
care  seems  to  propose  or  to  accept  such  a  justification  when,  after  having 
quoted  the  phrase  of  Hilbert:  "Let  us  consider  the  object  I,"  he  adds:  "Remark 
that  by  doing  this  we  by  no  means  imply  the  notion  of  number,  for  it  is  under- 
stood that  i  here  is  only  a  symbol. ..."  Doubtless,  but  it  is  a  symbol,  that  is 
to  say  one  object.  Will  M.  Poincare  say  that  that  implies  the  number  one? 
Or  will  he  grant  to  the  logisticians  the  same  liberty  as  to  Hilbert  ? 

28  [Cf.  note  26]. 

29  And  also  M.  Meray,  thus  giving  example  in  logic  to  other  mathema- 
tians. 

30  Notice  that  it  is  only  grammar  which  makes  us  use  the  sign  of  plural 
in  are  elements. 

81  Here  is  the  rigorous  definition  of  the  proposition  "x  is  a  w,"  that  Mr. 
Russell  has  communicated  to  me:  "x  is  a  u"  means:  "The  proposition:  '<i>x 
is  true,  and  u  has  the  relation  of  a  class  to  the  property  which  defines  it'  is 
not  false  for  all  values  of  x"  There  is  not  here  the  shadow  of  the  idea  of 
the  number  one,  but,  as  in  my  enunciation,  the  purely  logical  notions  of  false, 
negation  and  all.  This  definition  was  already  given  by  G.  Frege,  Grundgesetze 
der  Arithmetik,  Vol.  I,  1893,  P-  S3- 


506  THE  MONIST. 

These  considerations  reply  to  this  objection  of  M.  Poin- 
care's :  "A  relation  is  incomprehensible  without  two  terms ; 
it  is  impossible  to  have  the  intuition  of  the  relation  without 
having  at  the  same  time  the  intuition  of  its  two  terms." 
That  proves  nothing,  and  M.  Poincare  adds :  "And  with- 
out remarking  that  they  are  two,  for  in  order  that  the 
relation  may  be  conceivable,  it  is  necessary  that  they  should 
be  two  and  two  only."  It  is  not  the  question  to  know— 
and  it  is  a  psychological  question — if  we  "remark"  or  not 
that  they  are  two,  but  if  the  notion  of  the  relation  implies 
that  of  the  number  two.  Now  for  that  it  would  be  neces- 
sary that  it  implied  the  notion  of  the  class  formed  by  its 
"two"  terms;  and  that  is  obviously  not  the  case.  The 
proposition :  "x  is  the  father  of  y"  by  no  means  implies  the 
idea  of  the  class  formed  by  x  and  3;.  Besides,  it  often  hap- 
pens that  a  relation  (which  is  then  called  reflexive)  exists 
between  a  term  and  itself.  Would  it  be  maintained  then 
that  it  has  still  two  terms  ?  That  would  be  to  say  that  x 
is  at  the  same  time  one  and  two. 

The  only  logistical  formula  that  M.  Poincare  has  criti- 
cized in  itself  and  not  in  its  verbal  translation  is  one  given  by 
Burali-Forti.  M.  Poincare  says  on  this  point:  "I  understand 
thePeanian  language  too  little  to  dare  to  risk  a  criticism." 
This  confession  would  disarm  us  if  he  did  not  "risk"  this 
criticism  immediately  afterwards :  "I  fear  that  this  defini- 
tion begs  the  question,  for  I  see  the  figure  i  in  the  first 
member  and  'Un'  in  the  second  member."  M.  Poincare  has 
trusted  too  much  to  his  "intuition,"  and  it  has  deceived 
him.  Instead  of  "risking"  this  criticism  on  the  mere  wit- 
ness of  his  eyes,  he  ought,  conformably  to  the  fundamental 
rule  of  mathematical  method,  to  have  substituted  for  what 
is  defined  the  phrase  which  defines  it;  and  to  ascertain  if 
this  definition  really  begs  the  question,  he  had  only  to  refer 
to  the  definition  of  the  symbol  "Un." 

Now  M.  Burali-Forti  defines  "Un"  as  the  class  of  sin- 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  507 

gular  classes,  which  in  Russell's  definition  of  the  cardinal 
number  i.  This  definition  is  equivalent  to  the  one  which 
I  have  given  above  and  neither  of  them  implies  the  idea 
of  that  which  is  defined.  As  to  the  formula  which  M. 
Poincare  has  criticised,  it  means:  "i  is  the  ordinal  type 
of  the  ordered  classes  of  which  the  cardinal  number  is 
unity."  Thus  it  consists  in  defining  the  ordinal  number  i 
by  means  of  the  cardinal  number,  and  this  explanation  is 
enough  to  do  away  with  any  appearance  of  a  vicious  circle. 
So  we  see  how  "risky"  the  criticism  of  M.  Poincare  is. 
He  seems  to  consider  as  insignificant  the  formula 

i  E  No 

which  M.  Burali-Forti  deduces  from  his  definition.  M. 
Poincare  translates  it  inaccurately  as :  "One  is  a  number" ; 
and  then  makes  merry  at  the  expense  of  pasigraphy,  which 
"is  sufficient  to  demonstrate  that  one  is  a  number."  If  he 
had  read  the  memoir  of  M.  Burali-Forti — even  in  the  "inter- 
linear Italian  translation" — more  attentively  he  would  have 
known  that  "No"  means  ordinal  number,  and  perhaps  he 
would  have  found  the  formula  which  teaches  us  that  i  is 
an  ordinal  number  less  ridiculous.  Even  if  this  formula 
"taught"  nothing  to  M.  Poincare,  he  had  no  grounds  for 
judging  it  to  be  insignificant,  and  that  for  two  reasons. 
On  the  one  hand,  this  formula  is  sufficient  to  prove  that  the 
class  "No"  exists,  and  this  result  is  not  to  be  despised,  since 
M.  Poincare  attaches  so  much  importance  to  existence- 
theorems  and  wrongly  reproaches  the  logisticians  with 
neglecting  them.  On  the  other  hand  to  prove  that  all  the 
finite  whole  numbers  are  ordinal  numbers,  we  are  obliged 
to  use  the  principle  of  induction,  and  for  that  purpose  to 
set  out  from  the  fact  that  i  is  such  a  number.  However 
evident  or  trivial  this  fact  may  appear  to  M.  Poincare,  it 
was  important  to  demonstrate  it,  and  the  formula  at  which 
he  mocks  proves  the  conscientiousness  and  the  rigor  of  the 


508  THE  MONIST. 

logisticians.     The  pleasantries  of  M.  Poincare  are  then 
quite  pointless. 

As  for  the  paradox  discovered  by  M.  Burali-Forti  in 
the  theory  of  transfinite  ordinal  numbers,  and  from  which 
M.  Poincare  deduces  an  argument  against  logistics,  I  will 
only  say  that  this  contradiction  can  by  no  means  be  im- 
puted to  the  use  of  logical  symbols ;  and  the  proof  of  this 
is  that  mathematicians  who  are  total  strangers  to  logistics 
recognize  it,  discuss  it,  and  have  for  years  past  spent  vain 
efforts  to  solve  it.32  It  is  a  purely  logical  difficulty  which 
resides  in  the  principles  of  the  logic  of  classes,  that  is  to  say 
in  the  old  and  traditional  part  of  logic.  M.  Burali-Forti, 
in  a  communication  made  to  me,33  believes  that  the  contra- 
diction arises  from  the  different  meanings  that  are  given 
to  the  word  "ordinal  number/'  and  that  it  depends,  at  bot- 
tom, on  the  extension  and  the  properties  attributed  to  the 
concept  of  class.  Mr.  Russell  believes  that  it  can  only  be 
solved  by  restricting  or  even  sacrificing  the  notion  of  class ; 
broadly  speaking,  we  must  give  up  the  principle — appar- 
ently so  evident  and  clear  to  intuition — that  each  concept 
determines  a  class  which  is  its  extension.34  If  logistics 
has  enabled  us  to  discover  this  contradiction,  it  can  only  be 
considered  as  a  merit  and  not  as  a  reproach  for  it  proves 
that  it  is  an  instrument  of  precision  for  thought.  But  M. 
Poincare  is  more  exacting.  He  summons  logistics  to  re- 

32  Bernstein,  Math.  Ann.,  Vol.  LX;  Jourdain,  Phil.  Mag.,  1904-1905;  Rus- 
sell, Mind,  1905;  Hadamard,  Borel,  Lebesgue,  Baire,  Bulletin  de  la  Societe 
Math,  de  France,  1905;  Zermelo,  Borel,  Konig,  Schonflies,  Math.  Ann.,  Vol. 
LIX,  LX. 

88  [Cf.  for  fuller  details  pp.  228-229  of  Couturat's  original  paper]. 

84  See  Russell,  "On  some  difficulties  in  the  theory  of  transfinite  numbers 
and  order  types,"  Proc.  Lond.  Math.  Soc.  (2),  Vol.  IV,  1905,  pp.  29-53.  M. 
Poincare  concludes  hastily:  "Burali-Forti  and  Cantor  have  arrived  at  contra- 
dictory conclusions ;  thus  one  or  the  other  is  mistaken."  It  cannot  be  said 
that  one  of  them  is  mistaken  if  it  is  a  question,  as  Russell  shows,  of  a  con- 
tradiction of  principle,  of  a  kind  of  antinomy.  Thus  we  can  see  how  much 
the  conclusion  is  worth :  "consequently  pasigraphy  does  not  preserve  us  from 
error."  For  the  rest,  logistics  is  only  a  "method  of  infallibility"  (as  Leibniz 
said)  if  certain  premises  are  granted;  it  cannot  be  made  responsible  for  a 
contradiction  inherent  in  the  premises. 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  509 

solve  here  and  now  the  contradiction  which  has  become 
the  crux  of  mathematicians.  He  says  of  Mr.  Russell  and 
Dr.  Whitehead:  "If  they  could  have ....  purged  it  [the 
theory  of  infinite  numbers]  of  every  contradiction,  they 
would  have  rendered  us  a  signal  service."  The  logisticians 
are  not  obliged  to  solve  difficulties  which  stop  all  mathe- 
maticians, M.  Poincare  included,  and — as  if  they  were 
modern  Oedipuses  — to  reply  to  the  riddles  of  all  the 
sphinxes  which  are  encountered  in  science ;  but  if  they  suc- 
ceed where  others  have  failed,  M.  Poincare  will  be  good 
enough  to  remember  this  phrase,  and  do  honor  to  logistics 
for  the  solution. 

in. 

I  now  come  to  the  special  criticisms  that  M.  Poincare 
addresses  to  the  logisticians  on  the  subject  of  their  philos- 
ophy of  mathematics  and,  in  particular,  of  their  theory  of 
whole  number.  In  the  first  place,  there  are  certain  argu- 
ments which  it  is  astonishing  to  find  him  using,  but  which 
fortunately  are  not  likely  to  impress  philosophers.  For 
example:  "The  definitions  of  number  are  very  numerous 
and  very  varied.  . .  .If  one  of  them  were  satisfactory,  no 
new  ones  would  be  given."  The  same  objection  might  be 
urged  not  only  to  every  philosophical  speculation — and  that 
is  the  usual  argument  of  sceptics  and  positivists — but  to 
every  scientific  theory ;  M.  Poincare  knows  this  quite  well. 
If  this  argument  had  any  value,  it  would  be  the  negation 
of  all  progress,  even  scientific  progress.  In  mathematics 
in  particular  there  exist  numerous  definitions  of  the  irra- 
tional number,  of  the  limit,  of  the  definite  integral,  and  so 
on.  Has  ever  any  one  concluded  from  this  that  all  these 
definitions  are  bad  ?  Certainly  not,  but  simply  that  certain 
ones  are  better  than  the  others,  without  these  others  being 
properly  speaking  defective  or  wrong.  For  the  rest,  if  this 
argument  were  to  be  taken  literally,  it  would  prove  at  the 


5IO  THE  MONIST. 

outside  that  all  the  definitions  proposed  are  bad  except  one, 
the  last.  Consequently,  the  argument  has  no  bearing 
against  Mr  Russell's  definition  as  long  as  this  definition 
is  the  last  proposed. 

M.  Poincare  is  surprised  that  the  logisticians  define 
arithmetical  addition  by  means  of  logical  addition  which 
appears  to  him  to  rest  on  an  act  of  intuition  which  is  anal- 
ogous but  "more  complex/'  But  in  the  first  place  if  an 
act  of  intuition  is  really  necessary  for  one  or  the  other  of 
these  operations,  is  it  not  advantageous  and  meritorious 
to  define  the  one  by  the  other,  so  as  to  reduce  to  a  minimum 
the  number  of  acts  of  intuition  ?  Logical  addition  is  not  an 
invention  of  the  logisticians ;  it  has  existed  at  all  times  and 
in  all  minds.  It  is  the  combination  which  the  conjunction 
and  expresses  in  the  phrases,  "  the  French  and  the  Eng- 
lish," "philosophers  and  mathematicians."  Logic,  even 
classical  logic,  cannot  dispense  with  it.  Thus  it  is  not  ar- 
bitrarily, as  M.  Poincare  seems  to  believe,  that  this  notion 
is  introduced  "into  the  chapter  headed  'Logic.' '  Given 
that  it  is  indispensable  to  logic,  the  whole  question  is  to 
know  if  it  can  be  used  to  define  arithmetical  addition.  This 
idea  is  too  natural  for  Peano  and  Russell  to  have  been  the 
first  to  do  it;  it  is  already  clearly  expressed  in  the  work  of 
Lambert.  To  refute  it,  M.  Poincare  ought  to  have  shown 
how  and  why  arithmetical  addition  cannot  be  defined  by 
means  of  logical  addition,  and  consequently  ought  to  have 
criticized  Whitehead's35  formal  definition  of  it.  Or,  if  he 
believes  that  the  notion  of  logical  addition  is  "more  com- 
plex" than  that  of  arithmetical  addition,  he  should  try  to 
define  the  first  by  means  of  the  second.  That  is  the  best 
means  of  proving  that  mathematics  is  independent  of  logic. 
Meanwhile,  he  ought  to  allow  the  logisticians  to  observe 
the  classical  precept  that  principles  must  not  be  multiplied 
without  necessity. 

"Amer.  Journ.  of  Math.,  Vol.  XXIV,  1902. 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  511 

M.  Poincare  solemnly  accuses  the  logisticians  of  hav- 
ing violated  two  rules  of  method.  The  first  consists  in 
this :  Every  mathematical  definition  supposes  the  existence 
of  the  object  defined  and  is  only  valid  on  this  condition. 
But  this  condition  is  by  no  means  a  necessary  rule.  It  is 
useless  to  invoke  the  opinion  of  John  Stuart  Mill,  whose 
authority  is  rather  mediocre  in  the  logic  of  mathematics. 
The  condition  that  M.  Poincare  wishes  to  impose  on  logis- 
ticians is  absolutely  gratuitous  and  is  not  acknowledged 
by  the  most  rigorous  mathematicians.  A  definition  is  no 
more  than  the  giving  of  a  name;  it  by  no  means  supposes 
the  existence  of  its  object.  We  can  very  well  define  a  prob- 
lematical object,  and  then  prove  that  it  does  not  exist.  Thus 
Euclid  denotes  by  a  certain  sign  "the  greatest  prime  num- 
ber/' and  then  demonstrates  that  it  does  not  exist.  We 
define  the  derivative  or  the  integral  of  a  function  in  gen- 
eral, without  supposing  that  every  function  has  a  derivative 
or  an  integral.  What  M.  Poincare  wished  to  say  or  ought 
to  have  said  is,  on  the  other  hand,  that  a  definition  does 
not  imply  the  existence  of  the  object  defined,  and  this  exist- 
ence must  be  proved  or  postulated  if  we  wish  to  be  able  to 
use  it  in  further  reasonings.  This36  is  a  well-known  rule 
of  mathematical  method,  and  it  is  enough  to  run  through 
Peano's  Formulaire  to  see  that  each  definition  is  accom- 
panied, when  there  is  occasion,  by  an  existence-theorem 
which  usually  determines  the  conditions  under  which  the 
object  defined  exists. 

M.  Poincare  says  that  "in  mathematics  the  word  exists 
can  only  have  one  meaning,  it  means  'is  exempt  from  con- 
tradiction.9 "  I  am  sorry  to  contradict  him  on  so  elementary 
and  essential  a  point:  logical — or  mathematical,  it  is  all 
one — existence  is  quite  another  thing  from  the  absence  of 
contradiction.37  It  consists  in  the  fact  that  a  class  is  not 

88  Cf.  Les  Principes,  39. 

87  It  is  a  curious  thing  that  this  conception  of  logical  existence  only  appears 
admissible  in  a  panlogism  analogous  to  that  of  Leibniz,  and  where  the  exten- 


THE  MONIST. 

empty;  that  is  to  say  that  at  least  one  member  of  it  exists, 
and  this  means  by  definition  that  the  class  in  question  is 
not  null.  It  is  exactly  for  that  reason  that  it  is  the  custom 
of  mathematicians  to  prove  the  existence  of  a  class  by 
giving  an  example,  that  is  to  say  by  indicating  an  individual 
which  belongs  to  this  class ;  and  they  have  no  other  means 
for  proving  an  existence-theorem — unless  they  reduce  it  to 
a  preceding  theorem  or  postulate  of  existence.38 

But,  it  will  be  said,  how  is  the  existence  of  the  individual 
which  is  used  as  an  example  proved  ?  Must  not  this  exist- 
ence be  established  in  order  that  the  existence  of  the  class 
of  which  it  is  a  part  may  be  deduced  ?  Although  this  asser- 
tion may  seem  paradoxical,  the  existence  of  an  individual 
as  such  is  not  demonstrated.  The  individuals,  by  the  mere 
fact  that  they  are  individuals,  are  always  considered  as 
existing;  or  rather  the  question  does  not  arise  for  them 
since  logical  existence  is  a  property  of  classes  and  not  of 
individuals.39  We  never  have  to  express  that  an  individual 
exists,  absolutely  speaking,  but  only  that  it  exists  in  a  class, 
that  is  to  say,  is  an  element  of  it.40  When  an  individual 
is  defined  by  means  of  general  terms,  its  existence  is  demon- 
strated in  two  stages :  This  individual  being  defined  as  the 
u  (u  being  a  certain  class),  we  demonstrate  that  the  class 
u  is  not  null,  and  then  that  it  is  a  singular  class.  The  defi- 

sion  of  concepts  would  be  absolutely  determined  by  their  comprehension.  For 
example,  Leibniz  and  his  disciples  believed  that  if  "No  man  is  a  stone,"  that 
is  to  say,  if  no  "men-stones"  exist,  it  is  because  the  concepts  man  and  stone 
respectively  contain  contradictory  elements  (such  as  living  and  not-living). 

[On  the  following  discussion  of  the  "existence"  of  classes  and  individuals, 
cf.  my  remarks  in  The  Monist ,  Jan.,  1910,  Vol.  XX.,  pp.  113-116. — Tr.] 

88  It  is  enough  to  have  a  proposition  of  the  form :  "x  is  a  member  of  «,"  to 
be  able  to  conclude  that  the  class  u  exists. 

89  Of  course,  classes  themselves  can  be  considered  as   individuals  with 
respect  to  classes  of  classes,  but  then  they  "exist"  even  when  they  are  null. 

40  M.  Poincare  thinks  it  necessary  to  add  to  Peano's  postulate  the  follow- 
ing: "Every  integer  has  one  which  follows  it."  He  does  not  see  that  this 
postulate,  which  he  believes  new,  is  contained  in  the  third  postulate :  "The 
consecutive  of  an  integer  is  an  integer."  In  fact,  this  implies  that  the  con- 
secutive referred  to  exists  as  an  individual  of  a  class,  and  even  that  it  is 
unique,  for  otherwise  we  would  say  that  the  consecutives  are  contained  in  the 
class  of  integers. 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  513 

nition  of  the  individual  is  then  justified.41  But  what  we 
really  demonstrate  is  not  the  existence  of  the  individual  as 
such  but  the  existence  of  the  class  to  which  it  belongs.42 

In  all  of  this  there  is  no  question  of  contradiction. 
What  then  is  the  relation  between  the  existence  of  a  class 
and  the  absence  of  contradiction  in  its  definition?  It  con- 
sists in  this :  If  a  definition  is  contradictory,  no  individual 
fulfils  its  conditions,  and  consequently  the  corresponding 
class  does  not  exist.  Contradiction  is  then  a  purely  nega- 
tive criterion  of  existence;  it  is  the  criterion  of  non-exist- 
ence. And  reciprocally,  if  a  class  exists,  that  is  to  say 
contains  an  element,  we  can  conclude  from  that,  as  M. 
Poincare  says,  that  its  definition  is  not  contradictory.  Thus 
existence  appears  as  the  criterion  of  non-contradiction. 
But  it  is  to  be  noticed  that  the  relation  between  existence 
and  contradiction  is  exactly  the  inverse  of  that  which  M. 
Poincare  affirms;  it  is  not  non-contradiction  that  proves 
existence,  but  it  is  existence  that  proves  non-contradic- 
tion.43 

It  is  then  arbitrary  and  misleading  to  maintain  that  a 
definition  is  only  valid  if  we  first  prove  that  it  is  not  con- 
tradictory. Besides,  it  would  be  interesting  to  know  how 
we  could  prove  directly  that  a  definition  or  a  system  of 
postulates  is  not  contradictory.  The  presence  of  a  contra- 
diction can  certainly  be  proved,  but  the  absence  of  every 
contradiction  is,  like  the  innocence  of  an  accused  person,  a 
negative  fact  which  cannot  be  proved  directly.  Hilbert 

41  It  must  be  noticed  that,  though  the  definition  of  a  class  has  no  need  of 
justification  (as  this  class  may  be  null)  the  definition  of  an  individual  must  be 
justified  by  the  double  demonstration  of  the  existence  and  uniqueness.    There 
is,  then,  no  contradiction  here. 

42  Cf.  Russell,  "The  Existential  Import  of  Propositions,"  Mind,  July,  1905. 
48  After  having  written  these  lines,  I  found  the  same  doctrine  stated  by 

G.  Frege  in  his  Grundlagen  der  Arithmetik,  §§94,  95  (1884).  "A  concept  is 
admissible,  even  when  its  marks  contain  a  contradiction ;  only  we  must  not 
suppose  that  anything  falls  in  its  extension.  But  from  the  mere  fact  that  a 
concept  does  not  contain  a  contradiction,  we  cannot  conclude  that  something 
falls  in  its  extension...."  (§94).  "The  non-contradiction  of  a  concept  can 
only  be  established  rigorously  if  we  prove  that  something  falls  in  its  exten- 
sion. The  inverse  would  be  an  error"  (§95). 


514  THE  MONIST. 

stated  in  1900  that  we  can  find  a  direct  demonstration  of 
the  compatibility  of  the  axioms  of  arithmetic;44  and  in  1904 
he  believed  that  he  had  found  such  a  demonstration.45  But 
this  demonstration  is  not  satisfactory,  in  the  opinion  of  M. 
Poincare  himself.  If  "M.  Hilbert  hides  himself,"  it  is  not 
"because  the  difficulty  is  too  great,"  but  because  the  prob- 
lems which  he  has  proposed  to  himself  appear  insoluble. 
M.  Padoa46  has  already  replied  to  Hilbert  by  recalling 
that,  in  his  own  theory  of  algebraic  numbers,47  he  has 
demonstrated,  by  the  exemplary  method  which  is  the  only 
one  possible,  the  irreducibility  of  his  postulates  and  their 
reciprocal  independence.  And  he  concluded  with  this 
phrase :  "The  contradictions  or  the  dependencies  of  propo- 
sitions can  only  be  demonstrated  by  deductive  reasoning 
while  non-contradiction  or  independencies  of  propositions 
can  only  be  demonstrated  by  verifications  (we  verify  that 
properly  chosen  interpretation  of  the  symbols  satisfy  or  do 
not  satisfy  the  propositions  in  question)."  In  fact,  a  con- 
tradiction or  a  dependence  is  translated  by  a  proposition 
of  non-existence  or  by  an  implication ;  while  a  non-contra- 
diction or  an  independence  is  translated  by  a  proposition 
of  existence  or  by  a  non-implication.  And  this  difference  is 
equivalent  to  that  of  universal  and  particular  propositions 
in  classical  logic.  We  know  that  we  can  only  establish 
really  universal  propositions  by  demonstration,  but  that  to 
establish  a  particular  proposition  it  is  enough  to  cite  a 
single  case  in  which  it  is  true.  In  general  we  have  no  other 
means,  for  we  cannot  deduce  it  from  universal  premises 
without  the  adjunction  of  some  particular  proposition. 

**  Communication  to  the  second  international  congress  of  mathematicians 
at  Paris  in  1900;  cf.  Bulletin  of  the  Amer.  Math.  Soc.,  1902. 

46  Communication  to  the  third  congress  at  Heidelberg  in  1904 ;  cf.  Monist, 
July,  1905.  [Hilbert's  paper  is  reprinted  on  pp._  263-279  of  the  third  edition  of 
his  Grundlagen  der  Geometric,  published  at  Leipsic  and  Berlin  in  1909]. 

46  "Le  probleme  no.  2  de  M.  D.  Hilbert,"  L'Enseignement  mathematique, 
Vol.  V,  1903,  pp.  85-91. 

47  Bibliotheque  du  (ier)  Congres  int.  de  Philosophic,  Vol.  Ill,  pp.  309-365 ; 
Revue  de  mathematique s,  Vol.  VII,  1901,  pp.  73-84. 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  515 

Now,  just  as  it  is  impossible  to  deduce  a  particular  from 
universal  premises — that  is  to  say  a  negation  from  many 
affirmations — it  is  impossible  to  prove  deductively  an  ex- 
istence or  a  non-implication  if  we  set  out  from  non-exist- 
ences or  from  implication.  Thus  the  direct  method  that 
Hilbert  and  Poincare  recommend  is  impracticable.  M. 
Poincare  has  no  right,  then,  to  require  of  the  logistician  a 
demonstration  which  Hilbert  could  not  furnish.  He  might 
just  as  well  convict  them  of  impotence  by  summoning  them 
to  take  a  bite  out  of  the  moon. 

In  default  of  a  direct  demonstration  M.  Poincare  sug- 
gests a  very  curious  method  of  verification.  To  prove  that 
a  system  of  postulates  is  not  contradictory,  it  would  be 
necessary,  according  to  him,  to  compare  two  by  two  all 
their  consequences  to  prove  that  "there  are  not  two  which 
are  contradictory  to  each  other."  But,  as  he  himself  imme- 
diately recognizes,  this  method  is  impracticable  if  the  con- 
sequences to  be  examined  are  infinite  in  number,  as  is  the 
case  in  arithmetic.  I  add  that,  in  fact,  it  has  never  been 
applied.  Nobody  has  ever  seen  a  mathematician  spend  his 
time  in  comparing  among  themselves  all  the  propositions 
of  a  theory  to  assure  himself  that  the  definitions  from 
which  he  started  do  not  contain  some  contradiction,  and 
that  consequently  the  entities  denned  really  exist.  Where 
would  we  be  if  we  had  to  make  such  a  verification  for  each 
new  definition  ?  But,  it  would  be  replied,  it  is  the  whole  of 
mathematics  which  constitutes  this  verification;  it  is  a  fact 
that  no  contradiction  between  any  two  propositions  has 
ever  been  met.  Very  well,  but  this  verification  a  posteriori 
is  as  valid  for  logistics  as  for  mathematics,  since  logistics 
merely  claims  to  formulate  the  primitive  principles  and 
definitions  of  mathematics.  For  example,  we  may  ask  if 
the  postulates  by  which  whole  number  is  defined  are  not 
contradictory.  Logistics  has  only  to  reply:  I  deduce  from 
them  all  the  theorems  of  classical  arithmetic;  vou  have 


516  THE  MONIST. 

never  found  the  least  contradiction  in  these  theorems  when 
you  made  them  rest  on  vague  and  confused  intuitions ;  why 
do  you  wish  that  there  should  be  any  more  contradiction 
in  them  at  the  present  time?  They  are  the  same  proposi- 
tions, merely  reduced  deductively  to  some  principles.  In 
any  case,  the  burden  of  proof  falls  on  those  who  believe 
that  these  principles  are  contradictory;  for  contradiction 
may  be  proved,  but  non-contradiction  may  not. 

The  method  in  question  is  not  only  practicably  inappli- 
cable and  unapplied  in  fact :  it  is  logically  illegitimate.  In 
fact,  it  is  not  enough  to  bring  two  propositions  together, 
to  discover  that  they  are  contradictory,  unless  the  contra- 
diction is  formal  and  explicit.  For  example,  there  is  no 
formal  contradiction  between  the  two  propositions :  "ABCD 
is  a  non-rectangular  parallelogram"  and  "ABCD  is  a  quad- 
rilateral which  can  be  inscribed  in  a  circle" ;  the  contradic- 
tion only  appears  when  we  know  the  properties  of  the  in- 
scribable  quadrilateral,  that  is  to  say,  when  the  conse- 
quences of  the  second  proposition  are  deduced.  To  bring 
to  light  the  implicit  and  latent  contradiction  of  two  postu- 
lates, it  would  be  necessary,  accordingly,  to  deduce  all  the 
possible  consequences  (in  number  infinite)  from  these  pos- 
tulates. That  presupposes  the  following  definition :  "Two 
propositions  are  contradictory  to  one  another  when  they 
have  consequences  which  are  contradictory  to  one  another." 
But  such  a  definition  is  illogical  because  it  contains  a  circle. 
Thus  M.  Poincare's  criterion  of  non-contradiction  implies, 
not  merely  an  infinite  regress,  but  also  a  vicious  circle. 

M.  Poincare  well  knows  that  the  method  which  he  pro- 
poses is  impracticable.  He  tries  to  correct  it  by  means  of 
the  principle  of  induction :  "Perhaps  there  may  be  a  means 
of  showing  that  a  new  reasoning  cannot  introduce  contra- 
diction, provided  that  we  suppose  that,  in  the  series  of  pre- 
ceding reasonings,  we  have  hitherto  met  with  none."  No- 
tice the  very  doubtful  form  in  which  this  hypothesis  is 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  517 

stated.  Indeed,  it  is  a  hypothesis  in  the  air,  which  rests 
on  no  example  and  on  no  precedent,  and  which  seems  to 
be  invented  merely  to  charge  the  logisticians  with  a  vicious 
circle.  Now,  not  only  is  it  not  true,  that  is  to  say,  nobody 
has  ever  used  so  strange  a  kind  of  reasoning,  but  it  is  im- 
probable. To  show  this,  let  us  see  what  further  indications 
M.  Poincare  gives.  He  supposes  that  "a  series  of  syllo- 
gisms" can  be  formed  from  the  starting-point  of  the  axioms 
as  premises;  then,  "when  we  have  finished  the  nth  syllo- 
gism, we  see  that  we  can  make  a  (n-f-i)th" ;  lastly,  we  can 
show  that,  "if  there  has  been  no  contradiction  at  the  nth 
syllogism,  there  will  not  be  at  the  (n+i)th."  All  these 
hypotheses  are  absolutely  gratuitous  and  contrary  to  all 
probability.  In  the  first  place,  mathematical  reasonings  do 
not,  in  general,  consist  in  a  linear  series  of  syllogisms; 
otherwise  the  type  of  mathematical  reasoning  would  be  the 
sorites.  Must  we  repeat  that  the  syllogism  is  by  no  means 
the  only  type  of  deduction,  and  that  there  are  many  other 
logical  principles  or  rules  which  enter  into  reasoning? 
Then,  the  simple  deductions  which  compose  a  reasoning 
to  not  arrange  themselves  in  a  linear  series,  as  M.  Poincare 
imagines;  the  image  of  mathematical  reasoning  is  not  a 
chain  but  rather  a  genealogical  tree.48  What,  then,  does 
the  number  of  reasonings  made  at  a  given  moment  signify 
if  their  linear  order  is  always  more  or  less  arbitrary,  and 
arises  solely  from  the  practical  necessity  of  enunciating 
them  in  speech,  because  time  has  only  one  dimension?  "The 
number  n  serves  to  count  a  series  of  successive  operations," 
says  M.  Poincare;  what  becomes  of  his  argument  if  these 
operations  are  not  successive  or  are  only  so  by  accident? 
Can  we  affirm  that  this  number  n  exists  at  each  instant  and 
that  it  is  well  determined?  We  can  count  simple  deduc- 
tions if  they  all  reduce  to  the  type  of  the  syllogism;  but 

48  Cf.  Les  Principes,  p.  286  [and  the  long  note  on  p.  238  of  M.  Couturat's 
article,  which  we  have  not  here  translated.  It  contains  the  detailed  writing 
out  of  a  simple  theorem  in  the  mathematical  logic  of  Peano]. 


518  THE  MONIST. 

how  are  we  to  count  heterogeneous  deductions  which  pro- 
ceed from  various  rules  ?  Will  it  be  said  that  each  applica- 
tion of  a  logical  principle  constitutes  a  unity  ?  But,  besides 
the  fact  that  all  the  principles  have  not  the  same  deductive 
importance,  it  can  happen  that  many  principles  occur  at 
once  in  an  elementary  deduction.  That  is  what  happens, 
notably,  when  one  intervenes  as  premise  and  the  other  as 
a  rule  of  deduction.  All  this  proves  that  the  number  of 
deductions,  whether  syllogistic  or  not,  has  no  objective 
reality,  and  that  any  numbering  of  them  is  arbitrary.  Con- 
sequently, how  are  we  to  admit  that  a  proposition  depend- 
ing on  this  number  can  be  established  and  concluded  from 
n  to  n-\- 1  ?  And  then  M.  Poincare  relies  on  his  hypothet- 
ical case  to  attribute  to  the  logisticians  a  vicious  circle 
which  they  have  not  committed.  "With  an  if,"  says  com- 
mon sense,  "we  could  put  Paris  in  a  bottle."  It  is  with  an 
if  that  M.  Poincare  arrives  at  attributing  a  paralogism  to 
the  logisticians. 

Unfortunately,  M.  Poincare  seems  to  forget  elsewhere 
all  his  if's  when  he  asserts  categorically  that  the  principle 
of  induction  is  necessarily  used  in  every  demonstration  of 
the  compatibility  of  the  axioms  of  arithmetic  or  of  any  sys- 
tem of  axioms.  For  example,  he  says:  "We  must  have 
recourse  to  processes  of  demonstration  where,  in  general, 
we  have  to  use  the  same  principle  of  complete  induction 
which  is  the  one  to  be  verified."  Would  it  not  be  believed 
that  the  fantastic  method  which  he  proposes  is  in  current 
use?  Elsewhere  he  cites  it  as  one  of  the  "possible  applica- 
tions of  the  principle  of  induction,"  as  if  this  application 
had  been  actually  made.  Finally  he  says,  on  the  subject  of 
the  theorem  of  Bernstein :  "If  ever  another  demonstration 
is  invented,  it  must  still  rest  on  this  principle,  since  the  pos- 
sible consequences  of  the  axioms  which  are  to  be  shown  to 
be  non-contradictory  are  infinite  in  number."  Thus,  it  is 
enough  that  we  have  to  do  with  an  infinity  of  propositions 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  519 

(or  of  any  objects)  in  order  that,  according  to  M.  Poincare, 
the  principle  of  induction  necessarily  intervenes.  He  has 
quite  forgotten  that  the  application  of  this  principle  pro- 
posed by  him  is  subject  to  extremely  restrictive  hypotheses. 
At  the  bottom,  he  seems  to  confuse  mathematical  induc- 
tion with  induction  pure  and  simple.  For  how  are  we  to 
conceive  that  from  the  absence  of  contradiction  in  a  series 
of  reasonings  we  can  infer  the  absence  of  contradiction  in 
the  following  reasonings  ?  Without  doubt,  if  this  inference 
was  certain  and  could  be  expressed  by  the  precise  formula : 
"If  no  contradiction  has  been  found  in  the  first  n  reasonings 
it  will  not  be  found  in  the  n-\- 1  first  ones,"  there  would  be 
an  occasion  to  apply  the  principle  of  induction,  and  the 
conclusion  would  be  equally  certain.  But  the  inference  in 
question  can  at  most  only  be  probable,  and  consequently  it 
only  constitutes  a  common  induction  and  not  a  mathemat- 
ical induction.  To  borrow  an  example  from  M.  Poincare, 
the  geometry  of  Lobachevski,  since  it  only  comprises  a  fin- 
ite number  of  theorems,  did  not  absolutely  prove  that  the 
postulate  of  Euclid  is  independent  of  the  other  geometrical 
axioms  (that  is  to  say  that  its  negation  is  compatible  with 
them)  ;  it  only  gave  this  proposition  a  probability  which 
was  greater  as  the  number  of  theorems  of  the  new  geom- 
etry became  greater.  But  there  is  always  an  abyss  between 
a  probability,  however  great  it  may  be,  and  an  apodictic 
certainty.  Now,  the  results  of  common  induction  are  char- 
acterized by  probability,  while  mathematical  induction  is 
a  rigorous  process  which  engenders  certainty.  If  then  the 
inference  that  is  drawn  from  reasonings  already  made  to 
future  reasonings  has  only  a  probable  value  (as  common 
sense — that  "sure  instinct"  to  which  M.  Poincare  refers— 
thinks),  it  rests  on  an  induction  pure  and  simple  and  not 
on  the  principle  of  mathematical  induction.49 

*9[The  fourth  section  of  M.  Couturat's  paper  occupies  pp.  241-247,  and  con- 
tains a  detailed  refutation  of  M.  Poincare's  remark  that  Mr.  Russell  had  not 
demonstrated  the  existence  of  the  integers.  M.  Poincare's  opinion  rested 


52O  THE  MONIST. 

The  second  principal  fault  with  which  M.  Poincare 
charges  the  logisticians  consists  in  that  they  surreptitiously 
change  a  definition :  "You  give  a  subtle  definition  of  num- 
ber and  then  you  think  nothing  more  about  it ....  and  when 
the  word  'number'  is  found  farther  on,  you  attach  the  same 
meaning  to  it  as  the  first  comer  would.  . .  .Here  is  a  word 
of  which  we  have  given  an  explicit  definition  A.  We  then 
make  use  of  it,  in  discourse,  in  such  a  way  that  it  implicitly 
supposes  another  definition  B."  That  is  a  very  serious  re- 
proach that  must  not  be  urged  without  proof  against  logi- 
cians so  rigorous  and  so  practised  as  Peano  and  his  collab- 
orators. Now  M.  Poincare  gives  no  proof  and  confines 
himself  to  general  reflections  on  method  which  affect  logis- 
ticians less  than  anybody  else,  for  there  is  continually  in 
these  reflections  a  question  of  "words"  and  of  "phrases." 
Mathematicians  who  reason  with  words  and  phrases  are 
doubtless  liable  to  attribute  to  a  term,  instead  of  the 
meaning  assigned  to  it  by  its  definition,  the  meaning  which 
current  use  gives  it.  But  it  is  exactly  to  avoid  these  illog- 
ical associations  and  implications  that  the  logisticians  use 
symbols  whose  meaning  is  solely  determined  by  their  for- 
mal relations,  and  which  are  manipulated  in  virtue  of  for- 
mal rules  of  calculation.  Has  M.  Poincare  already  for- 
gotten that  he  reproached  logisticians  with  reducing  rea- 
soning to  a  blind  mechanism,  that  is  to  say,  with  neglecting 
the  meaning  of  their  symbols  ?  "To  demonstrate  a  theorem 
it  is  not  necessary  nor  even  useful  to  know  what  it  means" ; 
"the  mathematician  has  no  need  of  understanding  what  he 

partly  on  a  misreading  and  partly  on  the  fact  that,  in  M.  Couturat's  popular 
book,  the  question  of  existence  was  rather  neglected  in  comparison  with  Mr. 
Russell's  work.  However,  in  Mr.  Russell's  early  work,  while  existence  was 
treated  at  length,  the  far  more  important  question  of  entity  was  not  con- 
sidered. Thus  the  justification  of  Mr.  Russell's  early  existence-theorems  does 
not  now  appear  to  be  quite  satisfactory,  and  accordingly  is  here  left  untrans- 
lated. The  second  part  of  the  fourth  section  is  also  untranslated  here.  It 
contains  a  refutation  of  M.  Poincare's  hasty  judgment  that  the  principle  of 
induction  is  not  the  definition  of  finite  number,  and  is  slightly  more  technical 
than  the  rest  of  M.  Couturat's  paper.  What  follows  is,  in  essentials,  M. 
Couturat's  fifth  section.] 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  521 

does."  The  two  reproaches  are  contradictory;  let  M.  Pom- 
care  leave  to  the  logisticians  at  least  the  advantage  of  "the 
logical  correction  of  reasonings"  which  compensates  for 
its  "formal"  and  almost  "unintelligent"  character.  In  any 
case,  all  the  general  and  vague  reasons  which  he  alleges 
to  support  his  criticism  return  against  it,  for  they  tend  to 
prove  that  the  logisticians  are  exempt  from  the  causes  of 
error  which  he  points  out. 

I  have  long  sought  in  the  articles  of  M.  Poincare  for  the 
precise  proofs  of  his  accusation.  I  believe  that  I  have 
found  one,  and  yet  I  am  not  quite  sure.  M.  Poincare  re- 
proaches Mr.  Russell  with  using  two  different  formulae  of 
the  principle  of  induction,  and  with  confusing  them  illegi- 
timately :  "A  number  may  be  defined  by  recurrence ;  on  this 
number  we  may  reason  by  recurrence:  these  are  two  dis- 
tinct propositions.  The  principle  of  induction  does  not 
teach  us  that  the  first  is  true,  it  teaches  us  that  the  first 
implies  the  second."  He  says  again :  "The  principle  of  in- 
duction does  not  mean  that  every  whole  number  can  be 
obtained  by  successive  additions ;  it  means  that,  for  all  the 
numbers  that  can  be  obtained  by  successive  additions,  we 
can  demonstrate  any  property  by  recurrence."  In  the  first 
place,  the  expression  "successive  additions"  is  not  precise. 
The  question  necessarily  arises,  "How  many  additions?", 
and  the  reply  is,  "a  finite  number" ;  but  the  finite  numbers 
are  characterized  by  the  principle  of  induction.  Conse- 
quently, M.  Poincare's  proposed  enunciation  means:  "For 
all  the  numbers  which  can  be  defined  by  recurrence  (or  by 
complete  induction),  we  can  demonstrate  a  property  by 
recurrence."  Now  that  is  a  wholly  analytical  proposition, 
and  almost  z.  tautology:  "All  the  numbers  which  verify 
the  principle  of  induction  verify  the  principle  of  induction." 
If  this  were  the  formula  of  the  principle  of  induction,  it 
would  be  an  analytic  judgment,  and  not  a  synthetic  judg- 
ment as  M.  Poincare  maintains. 


522  THE  MONIST. 

But  that  is  not  the  true  formula  of  the  principle  of  in- 
duction, and  it  is  incomprehensible  how  a  mathematician 
like  M.  Poincare  could  have  made  such  a  mistake.  It  is  not 
with  him  just  an  airy  remark,  for  he  returns  to  this  impor- 
tant question  at  the  end  of  his  second  article  and  gives  pre- 
cise expression  to  his  thoughts  in  the  following  terms :  "A 
whole  number  is  that  which  can  be  obtained  by  successive 
additions,  it  is  that  which  can  be  defined  by  recurrence .... 
A  whole  number  is  that  on  which  we  can  reason  by  recur- 
rence ....  The  two  definitions  are  not  identical ;  without 
doubt  they  are  equivalent,  but  they  are  so  in  virtue  of  a 
synthetic  a  priori  judgment;  we  cannot  pass  from  one  to 
the  other  by  purely  logical  processes."50 

Will  it  be  said  that  the  logisticians  have  invented  a 
new  enunciation  of  the  principle  of  induction,  which  they 
set  up  against  the  classical  enunciation?  By  no  means, 
they  have  only  translated  the  traditional  enunciation  into 
symbols.  And  what  is  still  stronger,  M.  Poincare  himself 
quoted  this  traditional  enunciation  at  the  beginning  of  his 
first  article:  "We  know  the  enunciation  of  this  principle. 
If  a  property  is  true  of  a  number  i,SI  and  if  we  establish 
that  it  is  true  of  n-\-i  provided  that  it  is  true  of  n,  it  will 
be  true  of  all  the  whole  numbers."  Now  that  is  one  of 
the  verbal  translations  of  the  formula  of  the  principle  of 
induction.52  M.  Poincare  cannot  then  dispute  the  exactness 
of  the  symbolic  formula.  Thus  he  accuses  the  logisticians 
of  surreptitiously  changing  a  definition ;  and  it  is  he  himself 
who,  in  one  and  the  same  article,  changes  the  definition, 
or  rather  the  enunciation,  of  the  principle  of  induction! 

BO[M.  Couturat,  on  p.  249  of  his  article,  formulates  thr<^  two  definitions 
in  symbols,  and  shows  that  the  passage  from  one  to  the  other  is  effected  by  a 
process  as  analytic  as  the  passage  from  the  proposition,  "Pompey  is  one  of 
the  AT'S  such  that  Caesar  conquered  x"  to  the  pioposition,  "Pompey  was  con- 
quered by  Caesar,"  or,  "Caesar  conquered  Pompey."] 

61  Or  of  the  number  o ;  that  comes  tc  the  same  thing  here. 
88  It  is  one  of  the  verbal  translations  that  I  have  given  in  Les  Principes, 
P.  55- 


FOR  LOGISTICS.  523 

To  prove  his  accusation  he  himself  commits  the  paralo- 
gism which  he  wrongly  attributes  to  them,  and  all  his 
reproaches  of  illogicality  fall  on  himself  alone.  If  I  had 
the  wit  of  M.  Poincare,  I  would  say  that  his  "adventure" 
is  quite  as  instructive  as  that  of  M.  Burali-Forti,  and  that 
it  ought  to  "warn"  the  adversaries  of  logistics  of  the  neces- 
sity of  being  circumspect. 

I  will  not  bring  up  the  conclusion  of  the  articles  of  M. 
Poincare  because  I  do  not  see  the  utility  of  carrying  the 
discussion  into  history  where  it  is  complicated  by  questions 
of  interpretation.  The  controversy  is  not  "between  Kant 
and  Leibniz,"53  but  between  M.  Poincare  and  the  logisti- 
cians.  Besides,  the  question,  as  M.  Poincare  has  put  it,  is 
not  a  question  of  general  philosophy  or  of  epistemology, 
but  of  pure  logic.  Admitting  the  principles  and  the  primi- 
tive ideas  of  the  logisticians,  M.  Poincare  has  maintained 
that,  setting  out  from  these  data,  they  cannot  build  up 
mathematics  without  another  postulate — an  appeal  to  in- 
tuition or  a  synthetic  a  priori  judgment ;  and  he  has  thought 
that  he  has  discovered  in  their  logical  construction  certain 
paralogisms  (beggings  of  the  question  or  vicious  circles). 
I  believe  that  I  can  conclude  from  the  above  discussion  that 
not  one  of  these  theses  is  proved,  and  that,  in  particular, 
the  logisticians  have  not  committed  any  of  the  logical  errors 
that  are  so  lightly  imputed  to  them.  I  have  too  high  an 
idea  of  the  wit  and  the  character  of  M.  Poincare  not  to  be- 
lieve that  he  will  form  a  more  just  and  more  favorable 
opinion  of  logistics .  .  .  when  he  has  studied  it. 

LOUIS  COUTURAT. 
PARIS,  FRANCE. 

63  [Monist,  April,  1912,  Vol.  XXII,  p.  256.] 


THE  LATEST  EFFORTS  OF  THE  LOGISTICIANS.1 

THE  logicians  have  attempted  to  answer  the  preceding2 
considerations.  For  that,  a  transformation  of  logistic 
was  necessary,  and  Russell  in  particular  has  modified  on 
certain  points  his  original  views.  Without  entering  into 
the  details  of  the  debate,  I  should  like  to  return  to  the  two 
questions  to  my  mind  most  important:  Have  the  rules  of 
logistic  demonstrated  their  fruitfulness  and  infallibility? 
Is  it  true  they  afford  means  of  proving  the  principle  of  com- 
plete induction  without  any  appeal  to  intuition? 

THE  INFALLIBILITY   OF  LOGISTIC. 

On  the  question  of  fertility,  it  seems  M.  Couturat  has 
naive  illusions.  Logistic,  according  to  him,  lends  inven- 
tion "stilts  and  wings,"  and  on  the  next  page :  "Ten  years 
ago,  Peano  published  the  first  edition  of  his  Formulaire" 
How  is  that,  ten  years  of  wings  and  not  to  have  flown ! 

I  have  the  highest  esteem  for  Peano,  who  has  done  very 
pretty  things  (for  instance  his  "space-filling  curve,"  a 
phrase  now  discarded)  ;  but  after  all  he  has  not  gone  fur- 
ther nor  higher  nor  quicker  than  the  majority  of  wingless 
mathematicians,  and  would  have  done  just  as  well  with  his 
legs. 

On  the  contrary  I  see  in  logistic  only  shackles  for  the 
inventor.  It  is  no  aid  to  conciseness — far  from  it,  and  if 

1  Translated  by  George  Bruce  Halsted. 

1  "The  New  Logics,"  in  The  Monist,  April,  1912. 


THE  LATEST  EFFORTS  OF  THE  LOGISTICIANS.  525 

twenty-seven  equations  were  necessary  to  establish  that  i 
is  a  number,  how  many  would  be  needed  to  prove  a  real 
theorem?  If  we  distinguish,  with  Whitehead,  the  indi- 
vidual x,  the  class  of  which  the  only  member  is  x  and  which 
shall  be  called  1  x,  then  the  class  of  which  the  only  member 
is  the  class  of  which  the  only  member  is  x  and  which  shall 
be  called  11  x,  do  you  think  these  distinctions,  useful  as  they 
may  be,  go  far  to  quicken  our  pace  ? 

Logistic  forces  us  to  say  all  that  is  ordinarily  left  to  be 
understood;  it  makes  us  advance  step  by  step;  this  is  per- 
haps surer  but  not  quicker. 

It  is  not  wings  you  logisticians  give  us,  but  leading- 
strings.  And  then  we  have  the  right  to  require  that  these 
leading-strings  prevent  our  falling.  This  will  be  their 
only  excuse.  When  a  bond  does  not  bear  much  interest, 
it  should  at  least  be  an  investment  for  a  father  of  a  family. 

Should  your  rules  be  followed  blindly?  Yes,  else  only 
intuition  could  enable  us  to  distinguish  among  them;  but 
then  they  must  be  infallible ;  for  only  in  an  infallible  author- 
ity can  one  have  a  blind  confidence.  This,  therefore,  is  for 
you  a  necessity.  Infallible  you  shall  be,  or  not  at  all. 

You  have  no  right  to  say  to  us:  "It  is  true  we  make 
mistakes,  but  so  do  you/'  For  us  to  blunder  is  a  misfortune, 
a  very  great  misfortune ;  for  you  it  is  death. 

Nor  may  you  ask:  Does  the  infallibility  of  arithmetic 
prevent  errors  in  addition?  The  rules  of  calculation  are 
infallible,  and  yet  we  see  those  blunder  who  do  not  apply 
these  rules  \  but  in  checking  their  calculation  it  is  at  once 
seen  where  they  went  wrong.  Here  it  is  not  at  all  the 
case;  the  logicians  have  applied  their  rules,  and  they  have 
fallen  into  contradiction;  and  so  true  is  this,  that  they  are 
preparing  to  change  these  rules  and  to  "sacrifice  the  notion 
of  class."  Why  change  them  if  they  were  infallible? 

"We  are  not  obliged,"  you  say,  "to  solve  hie  et  nunc  all 
possible  problems."  Oh,  we  do  not  ask  so  much  of  you. 


526 


THE  MONIST. 


If,  in  face  of  a  problem,  you  would  give  no  solution,  we 
should  have  nothing  to  say;  but  on  the  contrary  you  give 
us  two  of  them  and  those  contradictory,  and  consequently 
at  least  one  false ;  this  it  is  which  is  failure. 

Russell  seeks  to  reconcile  these  contradictions,  which 
can  only  be  done,  according  to  him,  "by  restricting  or  even 
sacrificing  the  notion  of  class."  And  M.  Couturat,  dis- 
covering the  success  of  his  attempt,  adds :  "If  the  logicians 
succeed  where  others  have  failed,  M.  Poincare  will  remem- 
ber this  phrase,  and  give  the  honor  of  the  solution  to 
logistic." 

But  no!  Logistic  exists,  it  has  its  code  which  has  al- 
ready had  four  editions ;  or  rather  this  code  is  logistic  itself. 
Is  Mr.  Russell  preparing  to  show  that  one  at  least  of  the 
two  contradictory  reasonings  has  transgressed  the  code? 
Not  at  all;  he  is  preparing  to  change  these  laws  and  to 
abrogate  a  certain  number  of  them.  If  he  succeeds,  I  shall 
give  the  honor  of  it  to  Russell's  intuition  and  not  to  the 
Peanian  logistic  which  he  will  have  destroyed. 

THE  LIBERTY  OF  CONTRADICTION. 

I  made  two  principal  objections  to  the  definition  of 
whole  number  adopted  in  logistic.  What  says  M.  Couturat 
to  the  first  of  these  objections? 

What  does  the  word  exist  mean  in  mathematics?  It 
means,  I  said,  to  be  free  from  contradiction.  This  M. 
Couturat  contests.  "Logical  existence,"  says  he,  "is  quite 
another  thing  from  the  absence  of  contradiction.  It  con- 
sists in  the  fact  that  a  class  is  not  empty."  To  say:  a's 
exist,  is,  by  definition,  to  affirm  that  the  class  a  is  not  null. 

And  doubtless  to  affirm  that  the  class  a  is  not  null, 
is,  by  definition,  to  affirm  that  a's  exist.  But  one  of  the 
two  affirmations  is  as  denuded  of  meaning  as  the  other, 
if  they  do  not  both  signify,  either  that  one  may  see  or 


THE  LATEST  EFFORTS  OF  THE  LOGISTICIANS.  527 

touch  a's  which  is  the  meaning  physicists  or  naturalists 
give  them,  or  that  one  may  conceive  an  a  without  being 
drawn  into  contradictions,  which  is  the  meaning  given 
them  by  logicians  and  mathematicians. 

For  M.  Couturat,  "it  is  not  non-contradiction  that 
proves  existence,  but  it  is  existence  that  proves  non-contra- 
diction." To  establish  the  existence  of  a  class,  it  is  neces- 
sary therefore  to  establish,  by  an  example,  that  there  is  an 
individual  belonging  to  this  class :  "But,  it  will  be  said,  how 
is  the  existence  of  this  individual  proved?  Must  not  this 
existence  be  established,  in  order  that  the  existence  of  the 
class  of  which  it  is  a  part  may  be  deduced?  Well,  no ;  how- 
ever paradoxical  may  appear  the  assertion,  we  never  dem- 
onstrate the  existence  of  an  individual.  Individuals,  just 
because  they  are  individuals,  are  always  considered  as  ex- 
istent ....  We  never  have  to  express  that  an  individual 
exists,  absolutely  speaking,  but  only  that  it  exists  in  a 
class."  M.  Couturat  finds  his  own  assertion  paradoxical, 
and  he  will  certainly  not  be  the  only  one.  Yet  it  must  have 
a  meaning.  It  doubtless  means  that  the  existence  of  an 
individual,  alone  in  the  world,  and  of  which  nothing  is  af- 
firmed, cannot  involve  contradiction;  in  so  far  as  it  is  all 
alone  it  evidently  will  not  embarrass  any  one.  Well,  so  let 
it  be ;  we  shall  admit  the  existence  of  the  individual,  "abso- 
lutely speaking,"  but  nothing  more.  It  remains  to  prove 
the  existence  of  the  individual  "in  a  class"  and  for  that  it 
will  always  be  necessary  to  prove  that  the  affirmation, 
"Such  an  individual  belongs  to  such  a  class,"  is  neither 
contradictory  in  itself,  nor  to  the  other  postulates  adopted. 

"It  is  then,"  continues  M.  Couturat,  "arbitrary  and 
misleading  to  maintain  that  a  definition  is  valid  only  if  we 
first  prove  it  is  not  contradictory."  One  could  not  claim 
in  prouder  and  more  energetic  terms  the  liberty  of  contra- 
diction. "In  any  case,  the  onus  probandi  rests  upon  those 
who  believe  that  these  principles  are  contradictory."  Pos- 


528  THE  MONIST. 

tulates  are  presumed  to  be  compatible  until  the  contrary  is 
proved,  just  as  the  accused  person  is  presumed  innocent. 
Needless  to  add  that  I  do  not  assent  to  this  claim.  But, 
you  say,  the  demonstration  you  require  of  us  is  impossible, 
and  you  cannot  ask  us  to  jump  over  the  moon.  Pardon 
me;  that  is  impossible  for  you  but  not  for  us,  who  admit 
the  principle  of  induction  as  a  synthetic  judgment  a  priori. 
And  that  would  be  necessary  for  you,  as  for  us. 

To  demonstrate  that  a  system  of  postulates  implies  no 
contradiction,  it  is  necessary  to  apply  the  principle  of  com- 
plete induction ;  this  mode  of  reasoning  not  only  has  noth- 
ing "bizarre"  about  it,  but  it  is  the  only  correct  one.  It  is 
not  "unlikely"  that  it  has  ever  been  employed ;  and  it  is  not 
hard  to  find  "examples  and  precedents"  of  it.  I  have  cited 
two  such  instances  borrowed  from  Hilbert's  article.  He 
is  not  the  only  one  to  have  used  it  and  those  who  have  not 
done  so  have  been  wrong.  What  I  have  blamed  Hilbert 
for  is  not  his  having  recourse  to  it  (a  born  mathematician 
such  as  he  could  not  fail  to  see  a  demonstration  was  neces- 
sary and  this  the  only  one  possible),  but  his  having  re- 
course without  recognizing  the  reasoning  by  recurrence. 


THE  SECOND  OBJECTION. 

I  pointed  out  a  second  error  of  logistic  in  Hilbert's 
article.  To-day  Hilbert  is  excommunicated  and  M.  Cou- 
turat  no  longer  regards  him  as  of  the  logistic  cult;  so  he 
asks  if  I  have  found  the  same  fault  among  the  orthodox. 
No,  I  have  not  seen  it  in  the  pages  I  have  read ;  I  know  not 
whether  I  should  find  it  in  the  three  hundred  pages  they 
have  written  which  I  have  no  desire  to  read. 

Only,  they  must  commit  it  the  day  they  wish  to  make 
any  application  of  mathematics.  This  science  has  not  as 
sole  object  the  eternal  contemplation  of  its  own  navel;  it 
has  to  do  with  nature  and  some  day  it  will  touch  it.  Then 


THE  LATEST  EFFORTS  OF  THE  LOGISTICIANS.  529 

it  will  be  necessary  to  shake  off  purely  verbal  definitions 
and  to  stop  paying  oneself  with  words. 

To  go  back  to  the  example  of  Hilbert :  always  the  point 
at  issue  is  reasoning  by  recurrence  and  the  question  of 
knowing  whether  a  system  of  postulates  is  not  contradic- 
tory. M.  Couturat  will  doubtless  say  that  then  this  does 
not  touch  him,  but  it  perhaps  will  interest  those  who  do 
not  claim,  as  he  does,  the  liberty  of  contradiction. 

We  wish  to  establish,  as  above,  that  we  shall  never  en- 
counter contradiction  after  any  number  of  deductions 
whatever,  provided  this  number  be  finite.  For  that,  it  is 
necessary  to  apply  the  principle  of  induction.  Should  we 
here  understand  by  finite  number  every  number  to  which 
by  definition  the  principle  of  induction  applies  ?  Evidently 
not,  else  we  should  be  led  to  most  embarrassing  conse- 
quences. To  have  the  right  to  lay  down  a  system  of  postu- 
lates, we  must  be  sure  they  are  not  contradictory.  This  is 
a  truth  admitted  by  most  scientists ;  I  should  have  written 
by  all  before  reading  M.  Couturat's  last  article.  But  what 
does  this  signify?  Does  it  mean  that  we  must  be  sure  of 
not  meeting  contradiction  after  a  finite  number  of  propo- 
sitions, the  finite  number  being  by  definition  that  which 
has  all  properties  of  recurrent  nature,  so  that  if  one  of  these 
properties  fails — if,  for  instance,  we  come  upon  a  contra- 
diction— we  shall  agree  to  say  that  the  number  in  question 
is  not  finite  ?  In  other  words,  do  we  mean  that  we  must  be 
sure  not  to  meet  contradictions,  on  condition  of  agreeing 
to  stop  just  when  we  are  about  to  encounter  one?  To  state 
such  a  proposition  is  enough  to  condemn  it. 

So,  Hilbert's  reasoning  not  only  assumes  the  principle 
of  induction,  but  it  supposes  that  this  principle  is  given  us 
not  as  a  simple  definition,  but  as  a  synthetic  judgment  a 
priori. 

To  sum  up : 

A  demonstration  is  necessary. 


530  THE  MONIST. 

The  only  demonstration  possible  is  the  proof  by  recur- 
rence. 

This  is  legitimate  only  if  we  admit  the  principle  of  in- 
duction and  if  we  regard  it  not  as  a  definition  but  as  a  syn- 
thetic judgment. 

THE  CANTOR  ANTINOMIES. 

Now  to  examine  Russell's  new  memoir.  This  memoir 
was  written  with  the  view  to  conquer  the  difficulties  raised 
by  those  Cantor  antinomies  to  which  frequent  allusion  has 
already  been  made.  Cantor  thought  he  could  construct  a 
science  of  the  infinite ;  others  went  on  in  the  way  he  opened, 
but  they  soon  ran  foul  of  strange  contradictions.  These 
antinomies  are  already  numerous,  but  the  most  celebrated 
are: 

1.  The  Burali-Forti  antinomy; 

2.  The  Zermelo-Konig  antinomy; 

3.  The  Richard  antinomy. 

Cantor  proved  that  the  ordinal  numbers  (the  question 
is  of  transfinite  ordinal  numbers,  a  new  notion  introduced 
by  him)  can  be  ranged  in  a  linear  series,  that  is  to  say  that 
of  two  unequal  ordinals  one  is  always  less  than  the  other. 
Burali-Forti  proves  the  contrary;  and  in  fact  he  says  in 
substance  that  if  one  could  range  all  the  ordinals  in  a  linear 
series,  this  series  would  define  an  ordinal  greater  than  all 
the  others ;  we  could  afterwards  adjoin  i  and  would  obtain 
again  an  ordinal  which  would  be  still  greater,  and  this  is 
contradictory. 

We  shall  return  later  to  the  Zermelo-Konig  antinomy 
which  is  of  a  slightly  different  nature.  The  Richard  an- 
tinomy (Revue  generale  des  sciences,  June  30,  1905)  is  as 
follows:  Consider  all  the  decimal  numbers  definable  by  a 
finite  number  of  words;  these  decimal  numbers  form  an 
aggregate  E,  and  it  is  easy  to  see  that  this  aggregate  is 


THE  LATEST  EFFORTS  OF  THE  LOGISTICIANS.  53! 

countable,  that  is  to  say  we  can  number  the  different  deci- 
mal numbers  of  this  assemblage  from  I  to  infinity.  Sup- 
pose the  numbering  effected,  and  define  a  number  N  as 
follows:  If  the  nth  decimal  of  the  nth  number  of  the  as- 
semblage E  is 

0,  i,  2,  3,  4,  5,  6,  7,  8,  9 
the  nth  decimal  of  N  shall  be : 

1,  2,  3,  4,  5,  6,  7,  8,  i,  i 

As  we  see,  N  is  not  equal  to  the  nth  number  of  E,  and 
as  n  is  arbitrary,  N  does  not  appertain  to  E  and  yet  N 
should  belong  to  this  assemblage  since  we  have  defined  it 
with  a  finite  number  of  words. 

We  shall  later  see  that  M.  Richard  has  himself  given 
with  much  sagacity  the  explanation  of  his  paradox  and  that 
this  extends,  mutatis  mutandis,  to  the  other  like  paradoxes. 
Again,  Russell  cites  another  quite  amusing  paradox :  What 
is  the  least  whole  number  which  cannot  be  defined  by  a 
phrase  composed  of  less  than  a  hundred  English  words ? 

This  number  exists;  and  in  fact  the  numbers  capable 
of  being  defined  by  a  like  phrase  are  evidently  finite  in 
number  since  the  words  of  the  English  language  are  not 
infinite  in  number.  Therefore  among  them  will  be  one  less 
than  all  the  others.  And,  on  the  other  hand,  this  number 
does  not  exist,  because  its  definition  implies  contradiction. 
This  number  in  fact  is  defined  by  the  phrase  in  italics  which 
is  composed  of  less  than  a  hundred  English  words ;  and  by 
definition  this  number  should  not  be  capable  of  definition 
by  a  like  phrase. 

ZIGZAG  THEORY  AND  NO-CLASS  THEORY. 

What  is  Mr.  Russell's  attitude  in  presence  of  these  con- 
tradictions? After  having  analyzed  those  of  which  we 
have  just  spoken,  and  cited  still  others,  after  having  given 


532 


THE  MONIST. 


them  a  form  recalling  Epimenides,  he  does  not  hesitate  to 
conclude:  "A  propositional  function  of  one  variable  does 
not  always  determine  a  class."  A  propositional  function 
(that  is  to  say  a  definition)  does  not  always  determine  a 
class.  A  "propositional  function"  or  "norm"  may  be  "non- 
predicative."  And  this  does  not  mean  that  these  non-predi- 
cative propositions  determine  an  empty  class,  a  null  class; 
this  does  not  mean  that  there  is  no  value  of  x  satisfying 
the  definition  and  capable  of  being  one  of  the  elements  of 
the  class.  The  elements  exist,  but  they  have  no  right  to 
unite  in  a  syndicate  to  form  a  class. 

But  this  is  only  the  beginning  and  it  is  needful  to  know 
how  to  recognize  whether  a  definition  is  or  is  not  predi- 
cative. To  solve  this  problem  Russell  hesitates  between 
three  theories  which  he  calls 

A.  The  zigzag  theory; 

B.  The  theory  of  limitation  of  size; 

C.  The  no-class  theory. 

According  to  the  zigzag  theory  "definitions  (proposi- 
tional functions)  determine  a  class  when  they  are  simple 
and  cease  to  do  so  when  they  are  complicated  and  obscure." 
Who,  now,  is  to  decide  whether  a  definition  may  be  re- 
garded as  simple  enough  to  be  acceptable?  To  this  ques- 
tion there  is  no  answer,  if  it  be  not  the  loyal  avowal  of  a 
complete  inability:  "The  rules  which  enable  us  to  recog- 
nize whether  these  definitions  are  predicative  would  be  ex- 
tremely complicated  and  cannot  commend  themselves  by 
any  plausible  reason.  This  is  a  fault  which  might  be  rem- 
edied by  greater  ingenuity  or  by  using  distinctions  not  yet 
pointed  out.  But  hitherto  in  seeking  these  rules,  I  have 
not  been  able  to  find  any  other  directing  principle  than  the 
absence  of  contradiction." 

This  theory  therefore  remains  very  obscure;  in  this 
night  a  single  light — the  word  zigzag.  What  Russell  calls 


THE  LATEST  EFFORTS  OF  THE  LOGISTICIANS.  533 

the  "zigzaginess"  is  doubtless  the  particular  characteristic 
which  distinguishes  the  argument  of  Epimenides. 

According  to  the  theory  of  limitation  of  size,  a  class 
would  cease  to  have  the  right  to  exist  if  it  were  too  ex- 
tended. Perhaps  it  might  be  infinite,  but  it  should  not  be 
too  much  so.  But  we  always  meet  again  the  same  difficulty ; 
at  what  precise  moment  does  it  begin  to  be  too  much  so  ? 
Of  course  this  difficulty  is  not  solved  and  Russell  passes  on 
to  the  third  theory. 

In  the  no-classes  theory  it  is  forbidden  to  speak  the 
word  "class"  and  this  word  must  be  replaced  by  various 
periphrases.  What  a  change  for  logistic  which  talks  only 
of  classes  and  classes  of  classes !  It  becomes  necessary  to 
remake  the  whole  of  logistic.  Imagine  how  a  page  of 
logistic  would  look  upon  suppressing  all  the  propositions 
where  it  is  a  question  of  class.  There  would  only  be  some 
scattered  survivors  in  the  midst  of  a  blank  page.  Apparent 
rari  nantes  in  gurgite  vasto. 

Be  that  as  it  may,  we  see  how  Russell  hesitates  and  the 
modifications  to  which  he  submits  the  fundamental  prin- 
ciples he  has  hitherto  adopted.  Criteria  are  needed  to  de- 
cide whether  a  definition  is  too  complex  or  too  extended, 
and  these  criteria  can  only  be  justified  by  an  appeal  to  in- 
tuition. 

It  is  toward  the  no-classes  theory  that  Russell  finally 
inclines.  Be  that  as  it  may,  logistic  is  to  be  remade  and 
it  is  not  clear  how  much  of  it  can  be  saved.  Needless  to 
add  that  Cantorism  and  logistic  are  alone  under  considera- 
tion; real  mathematics,  that  which  is  good  for  something, 
may  continue  to  develop  in  accordance  with  its  own  prin- 
ciples without  bothering  about  the  storms  which  rage  out- 
side it,  and  go  on  step  by  step  with  its  usual  conquests 
which  are  final  and  which  it  never  has  to  abandon. 


534 


THE  MONIST. 


THE  TRUE  SOLUTION. 


What  choice  ought  we  to  make  among  these  different 
theories  ?  It  seems  to  me  that  the  solution  is  contained  in 
a  letter  of  M.  Richard  of  which  I  have  spoken  above,  to  be 
found  in  the  Revue  generale  des  sciences  of  June  30,  1905. 
After  having  set  forth  the  antinomy  we  have  called  Rich- 
ard's antinomy,  he  gives  its  explanation.  Recall  what  has 
already  been  said  of  this  antinomy.  E  is  the  aggregate  of 
all  the  numbers  definable  by  a  finite  number  of  words, 
without  introducing  the  notion  of  the  aggregate  E  itself. 
Else  the  definition  of  E  would  contain  a  vicious  circle ;  we 
must  not  define  E  by  the  aggregate  E  itself. 

Now  we  have  defined  N  with  a  finite  number  of  words, 
it  is  true,  but  with  the  aid  of  the  notion  of  the  aggregate 
E.  And  this  is  why  N  is  not  part  of  E.  In  the  example 
selected  by  M.  Richard,  the  conclusion  presents  itself  with 
complete  evidence  and  the  evidence  will  appear  still  stronger 
on  consulting  the  text  of  the  letter  itself.  But  the  same 
explanation  holds  good  for  the  other  antinomies,  as  is  easily 
verified.  Thus  the  definitions  which  should  be  regarded  as 
not  predicative  are  those  which  contain  a  vicious  circle. 
And  the  preceding  examples  sufficiently  show  what  I  mean 
by  that.  Is  it  this  which  Russell  calls  the  "zigzaginess"  ? 
I  put  the  question  without  answering  it. 

THE  DEMONSTRATIONS   OF   THE   PRINCIPLE   OF  INDUCTION. 

Let  us  now  examine  the  pretended  demonstrations  of 
the  principle  of  induction  and  in  particular  those  of  White- 
head  and  of  Burali-Forti. 

We  shall  speak  of  Whitehead's  first,  and  take  advan- 
tage of  certain  new  terms  happily  introduced  by  Russell 
in  his  recent  memoir.  Call  recurrent  class  every  class  con- 
taining zero,  and  containing  n+i  if  it  contains  n.  Call 


THE  LATEST  EFFORTS  OF  THE  LOGISTICIANS.  535 

inductive  number  every  number  which  is  a  part  of  all  the 
recurrent  classes.  Upon  what  condition  will  this  latter 
definition,  which  plays  an  essential  role  in  Whitehead's 
proof,  be  "predicative"  and  consequently  acceptable? 

In  accordance  with  what  has  been  said,  it  is  necessary 
to  understand  by  all  the  recurrent  classes,  all  those  in  whose 
definition  the  notion  of  inductive  number  does  not  enter. 
Else  we  fall  again  upon  the  vicious  circle  which  has  en- 
gendered the  antinomies. 

Now  Whitehead  has  not  taken  this  precaution.  White- 
head's  reasoning  is  therefore  fallacious ;  it  is  the  same  which 
led  to  the  antinomies.  It  was  illegitimate  when  it  gave 
false  results ;  it  remains  illegitimate  when  by  chance  it  leads 
to  a  true  result. 

A  definition  containing  a  vicious  circle  defines  nothing. 
It  is  of  no  use  to  say,  we  are  sure,  whatever  meaning  we 
may  give  to  our  definition,  zero  at  least  belongs  to  the 
class  of  inductive  numbers ;  it  is  not  a  question  of  knowing 
whether  this  class  is  void,  but  whether  it  can  be  rigorously 
deliminated.  A  "non-predicative"  class  is  not  an  empty 
class,  it  is  a  class  whose  boundary  is  undetermined.  Need- 
less to  add  that  this  particular  objection  leaves  in  force  the 
general  objections  applicable  to  all  the  demonstrations. 

*       *       * 

Burali-Forti  has  given  another  demonstration.3  But  he 
is  obliged  to  assume  two  postulates:  First,  there  always 
exists  at  least  one  infinite  class.  The  second  is  thus  ex- 
pressed : 

#eK(K  —  iA)  .D  .u<vu. 

The  first  postulate  is  not  more  evident  than  the  prin- 
ciple to  be  proved.  The  second  not  only  is  not  evident,  but 
it  is  false,  as  Whitehead  has  shown;  as  moreover  any  re- 
cruit would  see  at  the  first  glance,  if  the  axiom  had  been 

•In  his  article  "Le  classi  finite,"  Atti  di  Torino,  Vol.  XXXII. 


536 


THE  MONIST. 


stated  in  intelligible  language,  since  it  means  that  the 
number  of  combinations  which  can  be  formed  with  several 
objects  is  less  than  the  number  of  these  objects. 

ZERMELO'S  ASSUMPTION. 

A  famous  demonstration  by  Zermelo  rests  upon  the 
following  assumption:  In  any  aggregate  (or  the  same  in 
each  aggregate  of  an  assemblage  of  aggregates)  we  can 
always  choose  at  random  an  element  (even  if  this  assem- 
blage of  aggregates  should  contain  an  infinity  of  aggre- 
gates). This  assumption  had  been  applied  a  thousand 
times  without  being  stated,  but,  once  stated,  it  aroused 
doubts.  Some  mathematicians,  for  instance  M.  Borel,  reso- 
lutely reject  it;  others  admire  it.  Let  us  see  what,  accord- 
ing to  his  last  article,  Russell  thinks  of  it.  He  does  not 
speak  out,  but  his  reflections  are  very  suggestive. 

And  first  a  picturesque  example:  Suppose  we  have  as 
many  pairs  of  shoes  as  there  are  whole  numbers,  and  so 
that  we  can  number  the  pairs  from  one  to  infinity,  how 
many  shoes  shall  we  have?  Will  the  number  of  shoes  be 
equal  to  the  number  of  pairs  ?  Yes,  if  in  each  pair  the  right 
shoe  is  distinguishable  from  the  left ;  it  will  in  fact  suffice 
to  give  the  number  2n — i  to  the  right  shoe  of  the  nth  pair, 
and  the  number  2n  to  the  left  shoe  of  the  nth  pair.  No,  if 
the  right  shoe  is  just  like  the  left,  because  a  similar  opera- 
tion would  become  impossible — unless  we  admit  Zermelo's 
assumption,  since  then  we  could  choose  at  random  in  each 
pair  the  shoe  to  be  regarded  as  the  right. 

CONCLUSIONS. 

A  demonstration  truly  founded  upon  the  principles  of 
analytic  logic  will  be  composed  of  a  series  of  propositions. 
Some,  serving  as  premises,  will  be  identities  or  definitions ; 
the  others  will  be  deduced  from  the  premises  step  by  step. 


THE  LATEST  EFFORTS  OF  THE  LOGISTICIANS.  537 

But  though  the  bond  between  each  proposition  and  the 
following  is  immediately  evident,  it  will  not  at  first  sight 
appear  how  we  get  from  the  first  to  the  last,  which  we  may 
be  tempted  to  regard  as  a  new  truth.  But  if  we  replace 
successively  the  different  expressions  therein  by  their  defi- 
nition and  if  this  operation  be  carried  as  far  as  possible, 
there  will  finally  remain  only  identities,  so  that  all  will  re- 
duce to  an  immense  tautology.  Logic  therefore  remains 
sterile  unless  made  fruitful  by  intuition. 

This  I  wrote  long  ago;  logistic  professes  the  contrary 
and  thinks  it  has  proved  it  by  actually  proving  new  truths. 
By  what  mechanism  ?  Why  in  applying  to  their  reasonings 
the  procedure  just  described — namely,  replacing  the  terms 
defined  by  their  definitions — do  we  not  see  them  dissolve 
into  identities  like  ordinary  reasonings  ?  It  is  because  this 
procedure  is  not  applicable  to  them.  And  why?  Because 
their  definitions  are  not  predicative  and  present  this  sort 
of  hidden  vicious  circle  which  I  have  pointed  out  above; 
non-predicative  definitions  cannot  be  substituted  for  the 
terms  defined.  Under  these  conditions  logistic  is  not  sterile, 
it  engenders  antinomies. 

It  is  the  belief  in  the  existence  of  the  actual  infinite 
which  has  given  birth  to  these  non-predicative  definitions. 
Let  me  explain.  In  these  definitions  the  word  "all"  figures, 
as  is  seen  in  the  examples  cited  above.  The  word  "all"  has 
a  very  precise  meaning  when  it  is  a  question  of  an  infinite 
number  of  objects;  to  have  another  one,  when  the  objects 
are  infinite  in  number,  would  require  there  being  an  actual 
(given  complete)  infinity.  Otherwise  all  these  objects  could 
not  be  conceived  as  postulated  anteriorly  to  their  definition 
and  then  if  the  definition  of  a  notion  N  depends  upon  all  the 
objects  A,  it  may  be  infected  with  a  vicious  circle,  if  among 
the  objects  A  are  some  indefinable  without  the  intervention 
of  the  notion  N  itself. 

The  rules  of  formal  logic  express  simply  the  properties 


538  THE  MONIST. 

of  all  possible  classifications.  But  for  them  to  be  applicable 
it  is  necessary  that  these  classifications  be  immutable  and 
that  we  have  no  need  to  modify  them  in  the  course  of  the 
reasoning.  If  we  have  to  classify  only  a  finite  number  of 
objects,  it  is  easy  to  keep  our  classifications  without  change. 
If  the  objects  are  indefinite  in  number,  that  is  to  say  if  one 
is  constantly  exposed  to  seeing  new  and  unforeseen  objects 
arise,  it  may  happen  that  the  appearance  of  a  new  object 
may  require  the  classification  to  be  modified,  and  thus  it  is 
we  are  exposed  to  antinomies.  There  is  no  actual  (given 
complete)  infinity.  The  Cantor ians  have  forgotten  this, 
and  they  have  fallen  into  contradiction.  It  is  true  that 
Cantorism  has  been  of  service,  but  this  was  when  applied 
to  a  real  problem  whose  terms  were  precisely  defined,  and 
then  we  could  advance  without  fear. 

Logistic  also  forgot  it,  like  the  Cantorians,  and  en- 
countered the  same  difficulties.  But  the  question  is  to 
know  whether  they  went  this  way  by  accident  or  whether 
it  was  a  necessity  for  them.  For  me,  the  question  is  not 
doubtful;  belief  in  an  actual  infinity  is  essential  in  the 
Russell  logic.  It  is  just  this  which  distinguishes  it  from 
the  Hilbert  logic.  Hilbert  takes  the  view-point  of  exten- 
sion, precisely  in  order  to  avoid  the  Cantorian  antinomies. 
Russell  takes  the  view-point  of  comprehension.  Conse- 
quently for  him  the  genus  is  anterior  to  the  species,  and 
the  summum  genus  is  anterior  to  all.  That  would  not  be 
inconvenient  if  the  summum  genus  was  finite;  but  if  it  is 
infinite,  it  is  necessary  to  postulate  the  infinite,  that  is  to 
say  to  regard  the  infinite  as  actual  (given  complete).  And 
we  have  not  only  infinite  classes;  when  we  pass  from  the 
genus  to  the  species  in  restricting  the  concept  by  new  con- 
ditions, these  conditions  are  still  infinite  in  number.  Be- 
cause they  express  generally  that  the  envisaged  object  pre- 
sents such  or  such  a  relation  with  all  the  objects  of  an  in- 
finite class. 


THE  LATEST  EFFORTS  OF  THE  LOGISTICIANS.  53Q 

But  that  is  ancient  history.  Russell  has  perceived  the 
peril  and  takes  counsel.  He  is  about  to  change  everything, 
and,  what  is  easily  understood,  he  is  preparing  not  only  to 
introduce  new  principles  which  shall  allow  of  operations 
formerly  forbidden,  but  he  is  preparing  to  forbid  operations 
he  formerly  thought  legitimate.  Not  content  to  adore  what 
he  burned,  he  is  about  to  burn  what  he  adored,  which  is 
more  serious.  He  does  not  add  a  new  wing  to  the  building, 
he  saps  its  foundation. 

The  old  logistic  is  dead,  so  much  so  that  already  the 
zigzag  theory  and  the  no-classes  theory  are  disputing  over 
the  succession.  To  judge  of  the  new,  we  shall  await  its 
coming. 

HENRI  POINCARE. 

PARIS,  FRANCE. 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY 

IN  THE  LIGHT  OF  THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  SCIENCE. 

Objectivity. 

SINCE  the  dawn  of  civilization  man  has  groped  after 
truth.  He  has  investigated  it ;  he  has  pondered  on  it ; 
he  has  made  guesses  and  proposed  hypotheses ;  he  has  ap- 
proximated truth  by  allegories,  foreshadowing  it  in  verse 
and  fable ;  and  since  he  began  to  count  and  to  measure  he 
has  reduced  the  results  of  his  inquiry  to  exact  statements. 

All  observations  are  necessarily  subjective,  but  man 
is  not  satisfied  with  subjective  truth,  he  wants  objective 
truth  and  objectivity  of  statement  is  the  ideal  of  science. 

Is  objectivity  impossible?  Must  we  abandon  our  ideal 
of  science  ?  It  seems  to  us  that  science  has  more  and  more 
in  its  various  fields  approached  its  ideal  of  objective  truth. 
Standard  measures  have  been  invented  and  perfected.  Time 
is  measured  by  a  pendulum  of  definite  size,  even  apparently 
trivial  factors  have  been  considered  such  as  latitude  and 
altitude;  and  our  precision  machines  testify  to  the  in- 
genuity of  man's  genius  in  his  attempt  to  eliminate  per- 
sonal equations  as  much  as  possible.  The  reliability  of 
scientific  computation  has  reached  a  marvelous  degree,  but 
it  is  almost  more  astonishing  that  we  are  still  dissatisfied 
and  that  our  measurements  of  minute  fractions  of  the  wave 
lengths  of  light  are  no  longer  exact  enough  for  our  needs. 

In  the  face  of  the  enormous  accomplishments  of  science 
in  approximating  the  ideal  of  objectivity,  a  new  school  has 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  54! 

risen  which  goes  so  far  as  to  deny  all  objectivity,  and  in- 
sisting upon  the  truth  of  relativity,  it  would  make  us  be- 
lieve that  objectivity  is  a  phantom. 

The  relativity  principle  was  first  pronounced  by  Ein- 
stein in  the  Jahrbuch  der  Radioaktivitdt  (Vol.  IV,  pp. 
411  ff.,  1907).  It  was  invented  to  account  for  certain  diffi- 
culties in  the  explanation  of  optical  and  electrical  phenom- 
ena by  considering  the  relativity  of  the  movements  in  a 
system  that  is  not  at  rest,  called  a  disturbed  system  in  con- 
trast to  quiet  systems.  In  all  quiet  systems  the  common 
laws  of  dynamics  hold  good  and  the  proposition  of  the 
relativity  principle  has  been  made  for  the  sake  of  account- 
ing for  the  laws  of  disturbed  systems. 

The  principle  of  relativity  is  an  a  priori  postulate  from 
which  certain  theorems  are  derived  whose  truth  is  to  be 
verified  or  refuted  by  experiment.  Mr.  Norman  Camp- 
bell says:1 

"The  principle  is  what  is  more  often  termed  a  'theory' 
— that  is  to  say,  it  is  a  set  of  propositions  from  which  ex- 
perimental laws  may  be  logically  deduced.  It  can  be  proved 
to  be  true  or  false  in  a  manner  convincing  to  everybody 
only  by  comparing  the  laws  so  deduced  with  those  found 
experimentally;  but  a  theory  which  never  conflicted  with 
experiment  might  yet  (as  I  hold)  be  judged  objectionable 
on  other  grounds,  and,  conversely,  a  theory  which  was  not 
in  complete  accord  with  experiment  might  yet  be  judged 
satisfactory/' 

Among  the  postulates  of  the  principle  of  relativity  there 
is  one,  counted  the  second,  which  presents  great  difficulties. 
It  proclaims  that  "The  velocity  of  light  determined  by  all 
observers  who  are  not  accelerated  relatively  to  each  other 
is  the  same  whatever  may  be  the  relative  velocities  of  the 
observer." 

1  See  "The  Common  Sense  of  Relativity"  in  The  Philosophical  Magazine 
for  April  1911,  pp.  502  ff. 


542 


THE  MONIST. 


An  unsophisticated  thinker  would  naturally  assume  that 
the  velocity  of  light  must  be  expected  to  increase  or  de- 
crease according  to  the  velocity  of  the  observer.  But  the 
relativist  assures  us  that  light  is  an  exception;  on  his  as- 
sumption light  is  like  a  shadow  whose  motion  depends  upon 
the  motion  of  its  body  representing  the  observer.  The 
relation  of  the  shadow  to  its  body  remains  the  same,  how- 
ever its  body's  (the  observer's)  velocity  may  change. 

The  question  as  to  the  velocity  of  light  is  a  question  of 
physics,  not  of  philosophy,  and  we  will  touch  upon  it  later. 
Here  we  will  state  only  that  the  main  objection  to  the 
relativity  principle  is  the  inference  which  implicates  our 
objective  ideal  of  science. 

Not  all  the  relativists  agree  on  all  points  of  their  doc- 
trine, and  contradictory  statements  are  not  uncommon. 
We  can  here  only  characterize  the  general  tendency  and 
will  not  enter  into  the  individual  interpretations  too  closely. 

Relativists  try  to  avoid  a  difficulty  which  we  grant 
exists,  but  is  not  insurmountable.  Idealists  of  former  days 
have  used  more  subtle  methods  to  dispose  of  the  belief  in 
objectivity  of  things,  of  time,  and  of  space.  They  have 
produced  only  quibbles  and  the  relativists  have  succeeded 
no  better ;  only  it  is  strange  that  the  movement  has  origi- 
nated among  the  physicists. 

In  a  former  article2  we  have  demonstrated  the  para- 
mount importance  of  relativity,  but  for  all  that  we  see  no 
necessity  for  abandoning  the  old  ideal  of  science.  On  the 
contrary  we  feel  inclined  to  insist  on  it  more  strongly  than 
ever.  We  do  not  deny  the  relativity  of  all  existence 
throughout  and  without  exception,  but  we  still  cling  to  the 
old  scientific  ideal  of  objectivity  and  we  can  not  see  that 
the  relativity  principle,  in  the  one-sided  sense  in  which  the 
relativity  physicists  uphold  it,  is  well  established. 

Having  discussed  in  the  article  mentioned    the   part 

""The  Principle  of  Relativity,"  Monist,  April,  1912. 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  543 

which  relativity  plays  in  scientific  method,  we  feel  inclined 
to  add  a  few  suggestions  concerning  the  significance  of 
the  recent  movement  among  physicists  who  emphasize  the 
principle  of  relativity  and  prophesy  that  through  it  a  new 
era  in  the  scientific  interpretation  of  the  world  will  have 
to  begin. 

We  have  seen  that  many  of  the  paradoxes  which  are 
proclaimed  by  the  relativity  physicists  disappear  on  close 
inspection,  for  the  contradictions  resolve  themselves  into 
purely  verbal  contrasts.  The  same  object  is  not  in  itself 
longer  or  shorter,  but  the  result  of  measurement  will  be 
different  according  to  the  conditions  under  which  the  meas- 
urements take  place.  And  further,  although  time  can  be 
eliminated,  although  it  may  be  treated  as  a  function  of 
space,  or  even  be  treated  as  a  kind  of  fourth  dimension, 
the  conception  of  time  will  nevertheless  still  remain  of 
great  convenience.  The  truth  is  that  we  must  subsume 
time  and  space  under  one  common  category  which,  with 
Kant  and  other  thinkers  of  well-established  classical  tra- 
dition since  the  days  of  Aristotle,  has  been  called  "form." 
We  must  always  bear  in  mind  the  interrelation  between 
time  and  space  and  view  the  two  as  the  forms  of  one  and 
the  same  reality.  Time  is  the  form  of  doing,  of  progressive 
action,  of  change,  of  events,  and  space  is  the  form  of  being, 
of  existence  in  its  juxtaposition  of  parts.  The  former  is 
the  order  of  procedure  in  which  the  latter  is  transformed. 
Neither  can  be  thought  without  the  other,  and  the  two  are 
one.  The  principle  of  simplicity  requires  us  to  consider  both 
in  their  interrelation.  But  for  all  that  the  traditional  no- 
tion of  time  still  proves  the  best  method  for  rendering 
measurements  of  changes  intuitively  clear  while  an  elimi- 
nation of  time  as  proposed  by  the  Relativity  Physicists  is 
apt  to  obscure  the  issue;  and  we  come  to  the  conclusion 
that  experience  has  not  without  good  reasons  found  in  the 
proper  terms  "space"  and  "time"  a  very  convenient,  yea, 


544 


THE  MONIST. 


as  it  seems  to  me,  the  most  appropriate,  mode  of  represen- 
tation. 

It  is  strange  that  the  relativity  principle  has  been  pro- 
posed for  the  very  purpose  of  approximating  objective 
truth  with  greater  exactness,  but  instead  of  accounting 
for  inexactness  or  inaccuracies  in  results  and  for  apparent 
contradictions  by  taking  into  consideration  the  mistakes 
in  calculation  on  account  of  the  shifting  conditions  of  this 
world  which  is  a  constant  flux,  a  panta  rhei,  the  leaders  of 
the  new  movement  cancel  the  old  ideal  of  science  which 
has  guided  us  thus  far  and  propose  a  new  standard  strongly 
tinged  with  subjectivism,  built  upon  the  basis  of  the  rela- 
tivity of  all  existence. 

All  experience  is  a  mixture  of  objectivity  and  subjec- 
tivity :  it  is  due  to  the  interrelation  between  a  sentient  sub- 
ject and  the  sensed  objects.  So  far  science  has  tried  to 
eliminate  the  subjective  side,  the  personal  equation,  while 
the  relativity  physicists  deny  the  legitimacy  of  the  ideal  of 
objectivity,  or  as  they  call  it,  the  concept  of  the  real.  It 
is  true  that  in  clinging  to  the  facts  of  observation  without 
trying  to  eliminate  the  subjective  elements  and  thereby  to 
unify  our  results  in  an  objective  statement,  we  simplify 
our  calculations,  but  it  is  very  doubtful  whether  this  proce- 
dure can  be  generally  applied  to  other  than  optical  and  elec- 
trical phenomena.  Relativists  deem  the  theory  justified  if 
they  simplify  their  own  line  of  labors.  Mr.  Campbell  ex- 
claims in  his  enthusiasm: 

"Anything  more  beautifully  straightforward  it  would 
be  hard  to  conceive.  Not  only  is  the  result  magnificently 
simple,  but  it  furnishes  us  with  a  mathematical  instrument 
of  extraordinary  power.  In  place  of  the  elaborate  calcu- 
lations which  have  hitherto  been  necessary  in  dealing  with 
moving  systems,  all  that  we  have  to  do  now  is  to  solve  the 
problem  under  consideration  for  the  limiting  case  of  infini- 
tesimal velocity,  and  then  effect  a  mere  algebraical  trans- 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  545 

formation.  The  only  objection  that  seems  likely  to  be 
raised  is  that  the  principle  proves  too  much,  that  it  appears 
impossible  that  such  far-reaching  conclusions  can  be  drawn 
from  such  simple  assumptions :  the  only  difficulty,  in  fact,  is 
that  the  thing  is  too  easy." 

"The  crudest  arguments  based  on  the  oldest  theory  of 
light  lead  to  the  conclusion  that  the  rate  of  a  clock  as  ob- 
served by  a  certain  observer  must  change  with  the  relative 
motion  of  clock  and  observer.  For,  it  will  be  argued,  the 
observer  does  not  see  the  clock  'as  it  really  is  at  the  mo- 
ment/ but  'as  it  was  a  time  T  earlier,  where  T  is  the  time 
taken  for  light  to  reach  the  observer/  And  on  these  lines 
it  is  easy  to  show  that  the  apparent  rate  of  a  clock  moving 
away  from  the  observer  with  a  velocity  v  is  ( I  —  v/c) 
times3  the  rate  of  the  same  clocks  observed  at  rest.  It  is 
only  the  magnitude  of  the  change  concerning  which  the 
two  theories  differ. 

"  'Yes/  says  our  objector,  'that  is  all  very  well :  of 
course  the  apparent  rate  of  the  clock  changes  with  motion, 
but  does  the  real  rate  change?'  We  immediately  inquire 
what  the  'real  rate'  means.  He  is  at  first  inclined  to  assert 
that  it  is  the  rate  observed  by  an  observer  traveling  with 
the  clock,  but  when  we  inquire  relative  to  what  clock  that 
observer  is  to  measure  the  rate  he  becomes  uneasy.  He 
cannot  compare  another  clock  traveling  with  him,  for  if 
the  'real  rate'  of  one  clock  has  changed,  so  has  the  'real 
rate'  of  the  other ;  and  he  cannot  use  a  clock  which  is  not 
traveling  with  him,  because  he  admits  that  he  does  not  see 
such  a  clock  'as  it  really  is.' 

"Pressing  our  inquiries,  I  think  we  shall  get  an  answer 
of  this  nature.  'If  I  take  a  pendulum  clock  to  some  place 
where  gravity  is  different,  the  rate  of  the  clock  will  change. 
It  is  a  change  of  this  nature  which  I  call  a  change  in  the 

8  c  denotes  the  universal  velocity  whatever  it  may  turn  out  to  be.  See  ibid. 
P.  508. 


546  THE  MONIST. 

"real  rate,"  and  I  want  to  know  whether  there  is  any 
change  of  that  kind,  on  the  theory  of  relativity,  when  the 
clock  is  set  in  motion/  Now  why  does  our  objector  call  a 
change  of  the  first  kind  a  change  in  the  'real  rate'  ?  The 
reply  is  to  be  found  in  the  history  of  the  word  'real/  The 
word  is  intimately  associated  with  the  philosophic  doctrine 
of  realism,  which  holds  that  the  most  important  thing  that 
we  can  know  about  any  body  is  not  what  we  observe  about 
it,  but  its  'real  nature/  which  is  something  that  is  inde- 
pendent of  observation. 

Now,  of  course,  a  quantity  which  is  wholly  independent 
of  observation  cannot  play  any  part  in  an  experimental 
science,  but  there  are  quantities  which  are  independent  of 
observation  in  the  more  limited  sense  that  they  are  observed 
to  be  the  same  by  whatever  observer  the  observation  is 
made.  The  term  'real'  has  come  to  be  transferred  from  the 
philosophical  conception  to  such  quantities.  The  'real  rate' 
of  the  clock  is  said  to  change  when  it  is  transferred  to  a 
place  where  gravitation  is  different,  because  all  observers 
agree  that  the  rate  of  the  clock  which  has  been  moved  has 
undergone  an  alteration  relatively  to  that  which  has  not 
been  moved. 

"Now  in  the  conditions  which  we  are  considering  the 
observers  do  not  agree.  If  A  and  B,  each  carrying  a  clock 
with  him,  are  moving  relatively  to  each  other,  they  will  not 
agree  as  to  the  rate  of  either  of  their  clocks  relative  to 
A's  standard  or  to  B's  standard  or  to  any  other  standard. 
The  conditions  which,  in  the  case  of  the  alteration  of  gravi- 
tation, gave  rise  to  the  conception  of  a  'real  rate'  are  not 
present :  in  this  case  there  is  no  'real  rate,'  and  it  is  as  ab- 
surd to  ask  whether  it  has  changed  as  it  would  be  to  ask  a 
question  about  the  properties  of  a  round  square.  However, 
some  people,  who  in  their  eagerness  to  escape  the  reproach 
of  being  metaphysicians  have  adopted  without  inquiry  the 
oldest  and  least  satisfactory  metaphysical  doctrines,  are  so 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  547 

enamoured  of  the  conception  of  'reality'  that  they  refuse  to 
give  it  up.  Finding  that  the  observations  of  different  ob- 
servers do  not  agree,  they  define  a  new  function  of  those 
observations,  such  that  it  is  the  same  for  all  observers,  and 
proceed  to  call  this  the  'real  rate/  This  function,  according 
to  the  principle  of  relativity,  is  $n'  where  n'  is  the  rate  of 
the  clock  as  seen  by  an  observer  relative  to  whom  it  is  trav- 
eling with  the  velocity  v:  according  to  that  principle,  if 
we  substitute  in  that  function  the  appropriate  values  for 
any  one  observer,  the  resulting  number  will  always  be  the 
same.  So  far  no  overwhelming  objection  can  be  raised." 

What  the  relativists  call  "real"  we  would  call  objective, 
and  we  deem  the  ideal  of  objectivity  to  be  the  goal  of  sci- 
ence. Mr.  Campbell  has  much  to  say  on  the  concept  of 
reality : 

"It  is  the  great  merit  of  the  principle  of  relativity  that  it 
forces  on  our  attention  the  true  nature  of  the  concepts  of 
'real  time'  and  'real  space'  which  have  caused  such  end- 
less confusion.  If  we  mean  by  them  quantities  which  are 
directly  observed  to  be  the  same  by  all  observers,  there 
simply  is  no  real  space  and  real  time.  If  we  mean  by  them, 
as  apparently  we  do  mean  nowadays,  functions  of  the  di- 
rectly observed  quantities  which  are  the  same  for  all  ob- 
servers, then  they  are  derivative  conceptions  which  depend 
for  their  meaning  on  the  acceptance  of  some  theory  as  to 
how  the  directly  observed  quantities  will  vary  with  the 
motion,  position,  etc.  of  the  observers.  'Real'  quantities 
can  never  be  the  starting  point  of  a  scientific  argument ;  by 
their  very  nature  they  are  not  quantities  which  can  be  de- 
termined by  a  single  observation :  the  term  'real'  has  always 
kept  its  original  meaning  of  some  property  of  a  body  which 
is  not  observed  simply. 

"All  the  difficulties  and  apparent  paradoxes  of  the  prin- 
ciple of  relativity  will  vanish  if  the  attention  is  kept  rigidly 
fixed  upon  the  quantities  which  are  actually  observed.  If 


548 


THE  MONIST. 


any  one  thinks  he  discovers  that  that  principle  predicts 
some  experimental  result  which  is  incomprehensible,  let 
him  dismiss  utterly  from  his  mind  the  conception  of  reality. 
Let  him  imagine  himself  in  the  laboratory  actually  per- 
forming the  experiment:  let  him  consider  the  numbers 
which  he  will  record  in  his  note-book  and  the  subsequent 
calculation  which  he  will  make.  He  may  then  find  that  the 
result  is  somewhat  unexpected — to  meet  with  unexpected 
results  is  the  usual  end  of  performing  experiments, — but  he 
will  not  find  any  contradiction  or  any  conclusion  which  is 
not  quite  as  simple  as  that  which  he  expected. 

"There  is  one  further  point  sometimes  raised  in  con- 
nection with  the  principle  on  which  a  few  words  may  be 
said. 

"It  is  sometimes  objected  that  the  principle  'has  no  phys- 
ical meaning/  that  it  destroys  utterly  the  old  theory  of 
light  based  on  an  elastic  ether  and  puts  nothing  in  its  place, 
that,  in  fact,  it  sacrifices  the  needs  of  the  physical  to  the 
needs  of  the  mathematical  instinct.  That  the  statement  is 
true  there  can  be  no  doubt,  but  the  absence  of  any  substitute 
for  the  elastic  ether  theory  of  light  may  simply  be  due  to  the 
fact  that  the  principle  has  been  developed  so  far  chiefly  by 
people  who  are  primarily  mathematicians.  It  is  well  to  ask, 
can  any  physical  theory  of  light  be  produced  which  is  con- 
sistent with  the  principle? 

"The  answer  depends  on  what  is  meant  by  a  'physical 
theory/  Hitherto  the  term  has  always  meant  a  'mechan- 
ical theory/  a  theory  of  which  the  fundamental  propositions 
are  statements  about  particles  moving  according  to  the 
Newtonian  dynamical  formulae.  In  this  sense  a  physical 
theory  is  impossible  if  the  principle  of  relativity  be  accepted, 
for  the  same  reason  that  a  corpuscular  theory  of  light  is 
impossible,  if  the  undulatory  theory  of  light  be  accepted. 
Newtonian  dynamics  and  the  principle  of  relativity  are  two 
theories  which  deal  in  part  with  the  same  range  of  facts ; 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  549 

they  both  pretend  to  be  able  to  predict  how  the  properties 
of  observed  systems  will  be  altered  by  movement.  If  they 
are  not  logically  equivalent  they  must  be  contradictory :  in 
either  case  an  'explanation'  of  one  in  terms  of  the  other  is 
impossible.  It  can  be  easily  shown  that  they  are  contra- 
dictory: if  the  principle  of  relativity  is  true,  Newtonian 
dynamics  must  be  abandoned."4 

We  start  with  "the  facts  of  observation,"  and  try  to  es- 
tablish the  objective  state  of  things,  called  also  "the  real" ; 
but  relativists  ignore  the  latter,  and  since  every  observer 
has  his  own  particular  observation,  they  declare  that  there 
is  neither  real  time  nor  real  space.  The  real  is  ruled  out 
from  observation. 

Suppose,  however,  that  the  clocks  which  the  relativ- 
ist observes  wrere  the  heartbeats  of  the  relativist  himself 
and  the  observer  were  the  diagnosing  physician,  would  the 
relativist  insist  that  the  physician  had  better  drop  out  of 
sight  the  notion  of  reality,  that  there  is  as  little  sense  in 
asking  for  "the  real  rate"  of  his  heartbeat  as  it  is  absurd 
"to  inquire  whether,  if  all  triangles  had  four  sides,  all 
circles  would  be  square"?5  If  we  can  not  attain  an  abso- 
lutely correct  objective  statement,  we  keep  at  least  the 
ideal  in  view  and  this  ideal  is  not  an  empty  dream. 

The  relativity  principle  is  a  mathematical  view  of  cer- 
tain problems  worked  out  for  the  sake  of  most  minute 
measurements;  and  the  attitude  of  the  relativists  is  stern. 
If  the  facts  can  not  be  clearly  represented  by  it,  the  worse 
for  the  facts,  and  if  the  physicists  declare  that  their  phys- 
ical theories  are  incompatible  with  it,  a  new  brand  of  physi- 
cists has  to  be  manufactured  who  will  inaugurate  a  rela- 
tivist reform  in  physics. 

*This  conclusion  is  reached  by  Sommerfeld  in  a  paper,  Ann.  d.  Phys., 
XXXIII,  p.  684,  etc.  (1910). 

8  See  Campbell,  loc,  cit.,  p.  509.    The  comparison  is  not  appropriate. 


550 


THE  MONIST. 


Primary  Concepts. 

The  relativity  problem  would  never  have  originated 
had  the  philosophy  of  science  been  clearly  and  distinctly 
understood  by  physicists,  but  they  have  familiarized  them- 
selves very  little  with  even  the  problems,  let  alone  reached 
proper  solutions  which  explain  the  elementary  concepts  of 
our  scientific  terms,  the  difference  between  substance  and 
form,  between  energy  and  matter,  and  the  significance  of 
the  purely  formal  sciences. 

As  mathematicians  are  in  the  habit  of  starting  with  ax- 
ioms, so  the  relativists  begin  with  postulates  and  these 
postulates  come  in  collision  with  the  primary  concepts  such 
as  have  been  formulated  among  the  orthodox  physicists 
and  mathematicians  of  the  present  day. 

A  truly  scientific  view  will  brook  neither  axioms  in 
mathematics,  nor  postulates  in  philosophy,  nor  primary 
concepts  in  physics. 

There  has  been  much  talk  about  primary  concepts,  and 
arguments  have  been  offered  why  time  is  not  a  primary 
notion  or  why  we  should  let  it  pass  as  such.  The  truth  is 
that  time  as  well  as  space  are  two  methods  of  describing 
definite  relations.  Time  is  not  so  much  a  fourth  dimension 
of  space,  though  we  might  look  upon  it  as  if  it  were  such, 
time  is  the  measure  of  motion  and  space  is  the  scope  of  mo- 
tion. Both  time  and  space  are  presupposed  in  the  idea  of 
motion.  There  is  no  time  in  itself,  there  is  no  space  in 
itself.  What  Newton  and  others  with  him  call  absolute 
space  is  "space  conception"  and  what  they  call  absolute 
time  is  "time  conception."  Such  are  the  ideas  which  by 
pure  deduction  on  a  priori  arguments,  physicists  form  of 
time  and  of  space,  just  as  mathematicians  formulate  the 
general  conception  of  numbers,  of  distances  and  of  other 
relations,  angles,  areas,  etc. 

The  idea  of  primary  concepts  is  a  very  unfortunate  de- 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  551 

vice  to  lay  a  foundation  for  science.  The  faults  of  this 
method  will  not  show  so  long  as  specialists  are  concerned 
about  specialist  problems,  but  the  carelessness  of  taking 
anything  for  granted  shows  itself  as  soon  as  any  problem 
broadens  out  into  a  general  inquiry  when  its  connection 
with  universal  problems  is  questioned.  Such  primary  con- 
cepts are  assumed  to  be  undefinable  and  self-evident.  That 
opens  the  door  to  an  arbitrary  interpretation  as  to  the  na- 
ture of  space  and  time  and  energy,  and  gives  a  wide  berth 
to  mysticism. 

Science  brooks  neither  axioms  nor  primary  concepts. 
Science  starts  with  experience ;  it  quarries  out  of  experience 
the  stones  of  the  purely  formal  sciences  which  furnish  all 
the  methods  of  both  common  sense  knowledge  and  scien- 
tific inquiry.  The  most  general  characteristic  of  experience 
is  activity.  Activity  manifests  itself  in  change.  Change 
implies  motion;  it  means  either  change  of  place,  i.  e.,  mov- 
ing from  here  to  there,  or  change  of  combination,  viz.,  a 
moving  of  particles  among  themselves.  Change  inter- 
feres with  existing  relations,  it  modifies  the  old  interrela- 
tions and  establishes  new  interrelations. 

The  nature  of  relations  in  one  terse  term  is  called  form. 
The  word  "form"  comprises  both  outer  shape  and  inner 
structure,  and  all  interrelations  of  things  as  well  as  thoughts 
can  be  determined  by  the  laws  of  pure  form,  arithmetic, 
geometry,  logic,  etc.  Under  all  circumstances  change  mod- 
ifies relations  and  means  "transformation."  There  is  a 
transformation  in  the  juxtaposition  of  things  or  their  parts, 
and  there  is  a  succession  of  events.  The  scope  of  the  former 
we  call  "space,"  of  the  latter  "time";  or  better  from  the 
former  we  deduce  our  notion  of  space,  from  the  latter  our 
notion  of  time. 

Physical  inquiry  is  not  helped  by  calling  certain  fea- 
tures of  experience  "primary  concepts"  and  least  of  all 
(as  has  been  done)  should  space,  time  and  force, — these 


THE  MONIST. 

highly  complicated  constructions  of  a  priori  thought —  be 
beclouded  by  this  mystifying  name.  Both  time  and  space 
are  features  of  the  form  of  existence,  and  force  is  a  general 
term  for  that  feature  of  existence  which  marks  its  activity 
as  motion,  viz.,  as  change  of  place,  or  rather  as  that  which 
causes  changes  and  is  measured  by  the  resistance  over- 
come. 

If  we  adopt  the  relativist  principle  to  ignore  the  scien- 
tific ideal  of  objectivity,  i.  e.,  if  we  define  size  as  the  result 
of  measurement  and  moments  of  time  as  determinations  of 
measurement  by  units  of  duration,  without  regard  to  the 
ideal  of  coincidental  happenings,  and  a  common  standard 
of  time,  we  may  produce  incredible  statements  against 
which  common  sense  rebels,  and  Professor  Magie  in  his 
Presidential  Address,6  delivered  before  the  Physical  So- 
ciety and  Section  B  of  the  American  Association  for  the 
Advancement  of  Science,  at  Washington,  D.  C.  (December 
28,  1911),  says  in  comment  thereof: 

"A  description  of  phenomena  in  terms  of  four  dimen- 
sions in  space  would  be  unsatisfactory  to  me  as  an  explana- 
tion, because  by  no  stretch  of  my  imagination  can  I  make 
myself  believe  in  the  reality  of  a  fourth  dimension.  The 
description  of  phenomena  in  terms  of  a  time  which  is  a 
function  of  the  velocity  of  the  body  on  which  I  reside  will 
be,  I  fear,  equally  unsatisfactory  to  me,  because,  try  I  ever 
so  hard,  I  can  not  make  myself  realize  that  such  a  time 

is  conceivable I  do  not  believe  that  there  is  any  man 

now  living  who  can  assert  with  truth  that  he  can  conceive 
a  time  which  is  a  function  of  velocity  or  is  willing  to  go  to 
the  stake  for  the  conviction  that  his  'now'  is  another  man's 
'future'  or  still  another  man's  'past.' 

"One  of  the  members  of  this  society,  recognizing  our 
present  inability  to  conceive  of  relative  time,  and  conceiv- 
ing our  intuitions  of  space  and  time  to  be  the  result  of 

6  Published  in  Science,  February  23,  1912,  pp.  281  ff : 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  553 

heredity  operating  through  many  generations  of  men  who 
lacked  the  light  of  relativity,  once  proposed  to  me  that 
every  one  who  could  get  even  a  glimmer  of  the  notion  of 
relative  time  should  persistently  exercise  his  mind  therein 
and  teach  it  to  his  students,  in  the  hope  that  in  a  few  gene- 
rations the  notion  would  emerge  with  the  force  of  an  in- 
tuition. It  would  not  be  fair  to  leave  the  impression  that 
he  was  solemnly  serious  when  he  made  this  suggestion." 

Form  (i.  e.,  relativity)  is,  as  much  as  matter  and  energy, 
an  ultimate  generalization  and  may  be  called  a  fundamental 
concept  (not  a  primary  concept),  and  all  the  work  of  sci- 
ence is  a  tracing  of  transformations. 

It  is  essential  for  the  measurement  of  space  and  time  to 
employ  as  measures  uniform  units,  for  space  of  distance 
and  for  time  of  duration.  In  the  same  way  we  need  uni- 
form units  to  measure  force. 

Besides  a  quantitative  analysis  of  experience,  there  is 
a  qualitative  analysis  which  traces  such  transformations 
as  build  up  parts  into  a  higher  unit,  whereby  through  the 
interrelation  or  the  interaction  of  the  parts  a  new  thing 
originates  possessed  of  properties  which  are  absent  in  the 
parts  before  their  combination.7 

The  law  of  change  is  called  causality.  Cause  is  the 
motion  which  starts  the  process  of  transformation;  effect 
is  the  result  of  the  change ;  and  reason  is  the  general  rule 
(formulated  as  a  so-called  law  of  nature)  from  which  we 
understand  why  the  cause  must  have  this  effect.8 

The  so-called  law  of  the  conservation  of  matter  and 
energy  is  a  deduction  from  the  law  of  causality,  which  can 
be  made  as  soon  as  we  understand  that  all  happenings  are 
transformations,  for  if  all  changes  are  transformation,  the 

7  See  for  instance  the  author's  exposition  of  the  nature  of  quality  in  The 
Monist,  Vol.  XV,  p.  375.    See  also  Philosophy  of  Form,  p.  12. 

8  This  has  been  repeatedly  discussed,  e.  g.,  in  the  author's  Fundamental 
Problems,  pp.  79  ff. 


554 


THE  MONIST. 


amount  of  existence,  its  that,  remains  the  same,  only  its 
form  changes. 

While  investigating  the  several  problems  of  our  ex- 
perience, scientists  assume  that  they  deal  with  real  occur- 
rences and  thus  they  implicitly  grant  the  that  of  existence, 
popularly  denoted  "matter"  and  "energy,"  viz.,  thingish- 
ness  (or  with  a  Latin  term  "reality")  and  actuality.  The 
existence  of  ether  is  but  an  extension  of  the  concept  matter 
and  so  physicists  have  so  far  believed  in  the  existence  of 
ether ;  but  the  relativity  physicists,  in  their  anxiety  to  pro- 
pound original  ideas,  deny  the  existence  of  ether.  Says 
Prof.  William  Francis  Magie  in  his  above  mentioned  Presi- 
dential Address: 

"The  principle  of  relativity  in  this  metaphysical  form 
professes  to  be  able  to  abandon  the  hypothesis  of  an  ether. 
All  the  necessary  descriptions  of  the  crucial  experiments 
in  optics  and  electricity  by  which  the  theories  of  the  uni- 
verse are  now  being  tested  can  be  given  without  the  use 
of  that  hypothesis.  Indeed  the  principle  asserts  our  inabil- 
ity even  to  determine  any  one  frame  or  reference  that  can 
be  distinguished  from  another,  or,  what  means  the  same 
thing,  to  detect  any  relative  motion  of  the  earth  and  the 
ether,  and  so  to  ascribe  to  the  ether  any  sort  of  motion; 
from  which  it  is  concluded  that  the  philosophical  course  is 
to  abandon  the  concept  of  the  ether  altogether.  I  may 
venture  to  say  that  in  my  opinion  the  abandonment  of  the 
hypothesis  of  an  ether  at  the  present  time  is  a  great  and 
serious  retrograde  step  in  the  development  of  speculative 
physics.  The  principle  of  relativity  accounts  for  the  nega- 
tive result  of  the  experiment  of  Michelson  and  Morley, 
but  without  an  ether  how  do  we  account  for  the  interference 
phenomena  which  made  that  experiment  possible?  There 
are  only  two  ways  yet  thought  of  to  account  for  the  passage 
of  light  through  space.  Are  the  supporters  of  the  theory 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  555 

of  relativity  going  to  return  to  the  corpuscles  of  Newton  ? 
There  is  choice  only  between  corpuscles  and  a  me- 
dium, and  I  submit  that  it  is  incumbent  upon  the  advocates 
of  the  new  views  to  propose  and  develop  an  explanation 
of  the  transmission  of  light  and  of  the  phenomena  which 
have  been  interpreted  for  so  long  as  demonstrating  its 
periodicity.  Otherwise  they  are  asking  us  to  abandon  what 
has  furnished  a  sound  basis  for  the  interpretation  of  phe- 
nomena and  for  constructive  work  in  order  to  preserve 
the  universality  of  a  metaphysical  postulate." 

The  concepts  substance,  i.  e.,  matter  or  mass,  and  en- 
ergy are  ultimate  generalizations  as  much  as  form,  but  they 
are  very  different  from  form.  We  could  do  without  the 
words  "matter"  or  "ether"  by  the  use  of  some  other  indi- 
cation to  be  introduced  in  our  formulas  which  denotes  real- 
ity; but  that  would  not  disprove  the  truth  of  the  popular 
view,  which  describes  every  concrete  bodily  existence  as 
material,  nor  is  it  likely  that  the  old  method  of  nomencla- 
ture will  be  rendered  antiquated  or  erroneous. 

We  must  not  forget  what  matter  means.  Matter  is  a 
word  which  denotes  that  quality  of  objects  which  all  of 
them  have  in  common,  viz.,  objectivity.  An  object  is  a 
thing  that  is  objected  to  us,  that  offers  us  resistance,  that 
impresses  itself  upon  our  existence  and  thereby  affects  our 
senses,  and  by  objectivity  we  understand  the  general  prop- 
erty of  concrete  existence,  the  that  of  experience,  or  its 
reality,  viz.,  its  thingishness.  To  deny  the  reality  of  the 
real,  the  thingishness  of  things,  is  as  ridiculous  as  the 
opposite  mistake,  i.  e.,  to  think  of  reality,  or  objectivity, 
or  of  matter  as  a  mysterious  entity  in  itself.  There  is  no 
reality  in  abstracto,  for  every  that  of  existence  is  of  a 
definite  form  which  acts  somehow,  and  the  activity  of  things 
we  call  their  actuality,  or,  as  we  call  it  in  physics,  energy. 

The  same  problem  presents  itself  in  the  domain  of  the 
phenomena  of  ether,  i.  e.,  of  light  and  electricity.  There 


556 


THE  MONIST. 


are  some  good  reasons  to  assume  that  concrete  matter  has 
originated  by  a  contraction  or  condensation  of  a  more  prim- 
itive substance  which  for  all  we  know  may  prove  to  be  the 
luminiferous  ether,  that  thin  substance  which  has  been  as- 
sumed to  be  the  mediuni  of  light  and  electricity.  If  it  is 
claimed  by  modern  physicists  that  the  principle  of  relativity 
disposes  of  the  ether,  that  we  no  longer  need  it  and  can  dis- 
card a  belief  in  it  as  a  superstition,  that  all  physical  phe- 
nomena can  be  accounted  for  without  the  assumption  of 
an  ether,  we  confront  the  same  situation  as  in  the  theory 
of  energetics,  where  the  claim  is  made  "There  is  no  matter, 
all  is  energy." 

The  truth  of  this  position,  so  far  as  we  freely  grant  it, 
is  this,  that  all  scientific  explanation  describes  the  trans- 
formation of  things;  it  traces  the  changes  that  take  place 
according  to  the  laws  of  form  (mathematics  and  mechan- 
ics). In  experience  we  are  confronted  with  the  fact  that 
it  is  so,  but  the  scientist  inquires  into  the  factors  how  it 
has  become  so,  how  it  acts,  and  how  it  changes.  By  describ- 
ing the  how  in  formulas  (so-called  laws  of  nature)  we  de- 
note the  several  factors  with  algebraic  letters,  such  as  g  — 
gravity,  t  —  seconds  of  time,  d  =  the  distance  traversed 
by  a  falling  body  and  v  =  the  velocity  of  the  fall,  etc.,  and 
express  their  interrelation  in  equations,  as 

v  =  gt  and  d  =  l/2gtz. 

By  this  method  the  essential  features  of  natural  phe- 
nomena are  expressed  in  symbols,  and  he  who  has  been 
initiated  into  the  secret  meaning  of  the  symbols  and  the 
method  of  using  them,  will  be  able  to  predict  the  course  of 
events  if  he  is  in  possession  of  the  necessary  data. 

What  we  here  call  with  one  word  "essential"  Kirchhoff 
characterizes  in  two  words  "most  complete  and  most  terse," 
or  to  use  the  common  version  "the  most  exhaustive  and 
simplest."  We  deem  our  term  preferable,  and  we  under- 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  557 

stand  by  "essential"  all  that  which  is  efficient  to  produce  the 
result,  not  more,  not  less. 

We  speak  of  the  three  laws  of  Kepler  and  of  the  con- 
densed statements  of  the  law  of  gravitation  as  "formulas," 
and  this  term  truly  expresses  the  nature  of  these  general- 
ized descriptions  of  certain  types  of  uniformities.  They  are 
reductions  of  events  to  their  purely  formal  (i.  e.,  purely 
relational)  conditions,  and  these  purely  formal  conditions 
are  the  determinant  (i.  e.,  the  causative)  factors  in  all  pos- 
sible phenomena  of  a  special  type. 

This  is  not  a  new  truth.  How  old  it  is  may  be  inferred 
from  the  Greek  term  "formal"9  which  in  its  etymology 
means  "the  causal"  or  "the  causative"  because  the  Greek 
philosophers  describe  the  formal  factors  as  efficient  in  cau- 
sation. 

When  we  have  traced  the  essential  factors  of  a  certain 
type  of  changes,  the  scientist's  work  is  finished.  Whether 
mankind  will  ever  be  able  to  complete  a  scientific  compre- 
hension of  the  world  in  all  its  details,  must  be  regarded  as 
doubtful,  but  wherever  science  has  succeeded  in  discovering 
the  essential  factors  and  has  reduced  them  to  formulas,  we 
have  been  enabled  to  offer  for  every  such  phenomenon  a 
satisfactory  explanation. 

This  procedure  affords  us  an  insight  into  the  reason 
\vhy  the  course  of  a  certain  phenomenon  must  be  so,  why 
it  can  not  be  otherwise,  and  in  this  procedure  the  that  is  the 
basis,  the  how  is  the  method  of  cognition.  There  is  no  ex- 
planation possible  for  the  that,  for  the  reality  of  the  real, 
for  the  actuality  of  the  fact;  all  explanations  refer  to  the 
hozv.  The  that  is  a  brutal  fact,  and  the  ultimate  goal  of 
science  is  the  how,  the  answer  being  the  formulation  of 
laws  of  nature  which  explain  to  us  by  a  use  of  the  law  of 
pure  form  that  under  given  circumstances  definite  trans- 
formations will  take  place.  Knowledge  of  the  laws  of  na- 

0  rb  a/Ttw5«    derived  from  a-lria.  rr  cause. 


558  THE  MONIST. 

ture  helps  man  to  adapt  himself  to  nature  and  also  to  adjust 
his  surrounding  natural  conditions  to  himself. 

In  our  explanation  we  can  omit  the  that  as  a  matter  of 
course,  for  it  is  understood  that  reality  is  real.  We  can 
describe  the  purely  formal  relations  only,  which  are  the 
essential  part  of  explanations.  There  is  no  sense  in  ex- 
plaining the  that.  We  have  simply  to  state  whether  or  not 
a  formula  covers  actual  facts,  but  to  deny  the  that  and  say 
that  there  is  only  a  how  the  world  wags,  but  there  is  no 
world,  seems  to  us  a  proposition  that  misconceives  the  situ- 
ation. 

We  must  not  forget  that  such  a  word  as  substance,  de- 
noting here  both  "matter"  and  "ether"  or  existence  in  gen- 
eral, is  a  term  that  stands  for  objective  reality.  Ether  is 
the  that  of  the  phenomena  of  electricity  and  light,  as  matter 
is  the  that  of  bodily  objects,  declaring  that  they  are  real, 
that  they  are  concrete,  and  the  term  "substance"  covers 
any  kind  of  existence,  it  embraces  both  matter  and  ether 
or  whatever  the  ultimate  world-stuff  may  be  called.  There 
is  no  sense  in  denying  their  actuality,  and  all  that  may  be 
meant  by  such  a  denial  can  only  be  either  the  redundancy 
of  an  express  declaration  that  the  formulas  of  physics  refer 
to  real  processes,  or  a  denial  of  ether  or  of  matter  as  exist- 
ences in  themselves  apart  from  their  manifestations  in  defi- 
nite configurations  or  modes  of  motion  —  a  proposition 
which  nowadays  no  one  will  seriously  dispute. 

A  denial  of  the  existence  of  substance  (of  matter  and 
ether)  is  a  purely  verbal  quibble.  We  might  as  well  deny 
the  existence  of  energy  and  declare  that  there  is  no  energy, 
that  there  are  only  changes  of  place.  The  truth  is  that  the 
faculty  of  existence  which  manifests  itself  in  changes  of 
place  is  called  energy.  We  must  not  conceive  of  energy 

as  something  in  itself. 

*       *       * 

I  am  told  that  my  own  view  is  the  gist  of  the  principle 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  559 

of  relativity,  and  if  that  be  true,  I  would  gladly  hail  a  phi- 
losophy of  relativity  as  another  name  for  the  philosophy  of 
science.  I  have  myself  characterized  the  philosophy  of  sci- 
ence as  a  philosophy  of  form,  and  form  denotes  the  re- 
lations in  their  totality.  However,  I  would  add  that  the 
system  in  which  I  have  formulated  this  philosophy  of  sci- 
ence is  simpler  than  the  world-conception  of  the  relativity 
physicists,  besides  it  rests  on  a  more  solid  foundation  and 
is  absolutely  free  from  paradoxes. 

While  I  deny  that  we  can  dispense  with  the  idea  of 
objectivity  (be  it  called  matter,  or  ether,  or  substance)  I 
claim  that  we  need  make  no  mention  of  it  in  our  formulas. 
In  this  sense  we  can  dispense  with  the  mention  of  ether. 
While  I  would  not  take  the  several  paradoxes  of  time  and 
space  as  serious  and  deny  their  objective  truth,  I  grant 
that  by  a  little  confusion  of  thought  in  calling  time  or  space 
relations  the  results  of  our  different  measurements,  we  can 
legitimately  produce  these  paradoxes  by  exhibiting  the  in- 
evitable discrepancies  which  originate  through  measure- 
ments from  different  standpoints  as  objective  contradictions. 
Finally  I  consider  it  the  ideal  of  a  scientific  philosophy 
to  reduce  all  possible  occurrences  to  relations,  to  resolve 
them  into  questions  of  form,  to  look  upon  them  as  trans- 
formations, and  therefore  I  say  that  the  ultimate  aim  of 
science  is  to  describe  everything  in  formulas.  I  see  no  ob- 
jection to  the  relativist  claim  that  this  is  a  postulate  of  sci- 
ence. In  fact,  I  deduce  this  postulate  directly  from  my 
conception  of  reality  which  presents  itself  everywhere  in 
our  experience  as  transformation.  Thus  we  would  justify 
the  principle  of  relativity  on  the  basis  of  the  old  traditional 
basis  of  exact  science. 

The  main  claim  of  the  relativists  is  based  upon  their 
simplification  of  the  electromagnetic  equations,  and  this  is 
granted  even  by  the  adversaries  of  the  principle  of  rela- 
tivity. Professor  Magie  says: 


560  THE  MONIST. 

"It  is  surely  true  that  if  it  were  not  for  this  demand  of 
simplicity,  immediately  attainable  and  at  present  expressed 
in  the  electromagnetic  equations,  the  chief  incentive  to  the 
development  of  the  theory  of  relativity  would  be  wanting/' 

The  one  simplification  of  formulas  is  attempted  by  cer- 
tain relativists  by  a  generalization  of  time  and  space  into 
a  higher  four-dimensional  system,  and  they  call  it  a  four- 
dimensional  space.  We  may  note  incidentally  that  Wag- 
ner's Parsival  has  anticipated  the  doctrine  of  relativity, 
for  in  his  search  he  utters  the  mysterious  words:  "Zum 
Raum  wird  hier  die  Zeit!"  (Into  space  here  changeth 
time!)  The  relativists  might  as  well  have  called  their 
four-dimensional  space  a  four-dimensional  time.  We  ab- 
stain from  giving  it  a  name,  but  subsume  time  and  space 
under  one  and  the  same  category  as  "form"  which  enables 
us  to  view  time  and  space  as  two  inseparable  factors  of  the 
cosmic  system  of  interrelations,  and  we  deem  it  wise  to  re- 
member that  they  are  different.  If  the  relativity  physicists 
have  this  in  mind  and  do  not  mean  ulterior  mystifications, 
I  would  not  hesitate  to  join  their  ranks  on  this  point. 

*       *       * 

We  may  add  one  more  comment  about  simplification. 
Logical  possibilities  are  wider  than  actualized  reality.  Re- 
ality is  one  instance  among  many  others  which  are  not 
actualized.  The  fictions  of  fairy  tales,  of  Gulliver's  Trav- 
els, and  of  religious  myth  are  instances  of  it.  But  in  the 
domain  of  pure  logic  even  actually  absurd  conditions  pa- 
rade as  legitimate  potentialities.  Actual  space  has  three  di- 
mensions, but  metageometricians  have  invented  more-di- 
mensional spaces.  Why  not  ?  We  have  in  the  construction 
of  purely  logical  systems  the  undeniable  right  to  general- 
ize into  the  not  actualized  logical  possibilities  and  mathe- 
maticians can  not  be  restrained  from  building  up  a  pange- 
ometry.  While  Euclidean  space  is  homaloidal,  they  may 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  561 

create  all  kinds  of  curved  spaces,  which  are  all  legitimate 
before  the  tribunal  of  pure  logic,  if  they  are  but  consistent 
in  themselves.  The  main  gain  derived  from  such  construc- 
tions which  will  naturally  appear  to  the  average  man  of 
average  common  sense  as  gratuitous,  if  not  positively  non- 
sensical, consists  in  rising  to  a  higher  level  and  understand- 
ing from  this  higher  point  of  view  the  actualized  reality 
better  than  if  he  remains  on  the  terra  firma  of  a  limited 
sense-experience. 

It  might  help  our  comprehension  of  causality  as  a  trans- 
formation according  to  the  laws  of  form  to  conceive  the 
chain  of  causation  as  reversible,  that  the  condition  of  causes 
are  turned  into  effects  and  that  the  final  factors  that  bring 
about  the  effect  become  the  causes.  This  view  has  been 
humorously  worked  out  by  Fechner  who  for  this  purpose 
assumes  that  the  pendulum  of  events  will  go  on  for  a  while 
in  the  direction  it  takes  now,  but  the  time  will  come  when 
it  will  swing  back.  And  then  it  will  appear  to  us  as  quite 
natural  and  necessary  that  the  decayed  and  waste  material 
from  fields  and  polluted  rivers  pass  into  our  bodies  and  are 
changed  in  our  bowels  into  juice  to  go  forth  from  our 
mouths  on  the  dinner  table  as  lovely  fruit  or  cheese,  with 
bread  and  butter,  and  as  roast  venison  or  fish  to  go  back 
and  constitute  useful  parts  in  the  revived  animal.  It  would 
please  us  to  see  all  this  come  about  and  the  thought  of  the 
resurrection  of  the  lamb  under  the  butcher's  knife  would 
demonstrate  that  there  is  a  purpose  in  the  law  of  causation. 
We  would  be  accustomed  to  the  outcome  and  deem  it 
natural.  In  fact  some  notions  of  an  inverse  world  order 
in  the  golden  age  when  the  lamb  will  feed  on  the  wolf,  when 
the  deer  will  hunt  the  hunter,  when  the  rich  shall  be  poor 
and  the  poor  rich,  when  the  miserable  will  be  comforted 
while  the  fortunate  will  be  tortured  has  now  and  then  re- 
ceived serious  support  in  the  religious  hopes  of  the  dis- 
inherited classes  of  mankind,  and  we  may  find  in  the  New 


562  THE  MONIST. 

Testament  an  echo  of  this  belief  in  those  traditions  which 
come  down  to  us  from  Ebionite  sources,  the  parables  of  the 
foolishness  of  the  rich  and  the  benediction  of  the  poor. 
Dives  goes  to  Hell  while  Lazarus  is  carried  by  angels  to 
Abraham's  bosom.  Abraham  says  in  Luke  xvi:  25 :  "Son, 
remember  that  thou  in  thy  lifetime  receivedst  thy  good 
things,  and  likewise  Lazarus  evil  things:  but  now  he  is 
comforted,  and  thou  art  tormented."  No  mention  is  made 
that  Dives  was  wicked  and  that  Lazarus  was  good;  the 
only  argument  is  that  the  other  world  must  be  reverted  in 
its  order. 

A  view  of  this  kind  which  generalizes  the  mechanical 
constitution  of  the  world  and  sees  the  possibility  of  an  in- 
verted causation,  just  as  an  engine  may  be  reversed,  may 
widen  our  comprehension  and  simplify  our  formulas  of 
moral  action,  but  we  need  not  for  that  reason  believe  in 
its  actualization.  It  is  simply  an  instructive  lusus  imagina- 
tionis,  an  ingenious  and  helpful  fiction — like  our  conception 
of  four-dimensional  space. 

The  mathematician  who  limits  his  studies  to  the  Euclid- 
ean plane  will  understand  his  problems  better  if  he  becomes 
familiar  with  the  theorems  of  stereometry,  or  if  he  views  the 
figures  of  plane  geometry  as  projections;  or  again  if  he  re- 
gards a  certain  set  of  curves  as  conic  sections.  And  further 
many  problems  of  stereometry  find  a  simpler  formulation 
if  viewed  from  the  more  comprehensive,  though  purely 
imaginary,  view-point  of  a  four-dimensional  geometry.  All 
this  indicates  that  the  simplifications  of  which  the  relativity 
physicists  boast,  may  be  (and  I  am  inclined  to  believe  that 
they  are)  very  harmless.  For  all  I  can  say,  judging  merely 
from  the  acceptance  they  have  found,  they  must  be  true, 
but  I  can  not  see  why  they  should  be  subversive  of  the  sci- 
entific world-conception  of  the  past. 

A  peculiar  view  of  time  which  has  been  proposed  in  all 
seriousness,  although  common  sense  might  consider  it  as 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  563 

absurd,  is  the  concept  of  time  and  space  as  consisting  of 
discrete  ultimate  units.  Do  not  our  years,  and  days,  and 
our  hours  too  begin  at  definite  moments  ?  We  become  fifty 
or  sixty  years  old  suddenly  with  the  beginning  of  a  definite 
minute,  According  to  this,  time  would  run  in  jerks  like 
the  jumping  second  hands,  and  it  would  ultimately  consist 
of  infinitesimally  small  units  of  duration.  Space  also  would 
be  stippled  and  not  continuous.  Every  motion  would  have 
to  proceed  in  hopping  from  spot  to  spot,  and  the  surface  of 
a  plane  would  be  not  unlike  a  half-tone  picture  which  pro- 
duces the  impression  of  a  continuous  level  but  consists  in 
reality  of  different  dots  more  or  less  deeply  tinged  with 
ink.  Such  conceptions  of  time  and  space  are  quite  con- 
ceivable although  our  classical  and  well-established  views 
of  both  present  them  as  continua.  If  space  and  time  were 
actual  entities  endowed  with  positive  qualities,  if  they  were 
not  merely  potentialities  of  motion,  a  scope  in  which  we 
move  about,  we  could  discover  the  nature  of  space  by  ex- 
periment. However,  as  they  are  constructions  made  in  the 
abstract  domain  of  anyness  we  should  not  refuse  to  con- 
sider seriously  all  kinds  of  propositions  as  to  the  nature  of 
time  and  space.10 

In  comment  on  theories  of  this  kind  we  would  say  that 
duration  is  continuous,  but  time  consists  of  discrete  units 
of  duration ;  and  again  the  scope  of  motion  shows  us  an  un- 
interrupted expanse  while  geometry  exhibits  definite  lines 

10  The  present  number  of  The  Monist  contains  an  article  on  "Atomic 
Theories  of  Energy"  by  Mr.  Arthur  E.  Bostwick,  which  will  prove  of  great 
interest  even  to  those  who  do  not  accept  this  theory.  In  comment  we  would 
say  that  Mr.  Bostwick's  defense  of  an  atomic  theory  of  energy  is  certainly 
true  of  definite  amounts  of  energy,  and  his  theory  holds  good  also  in  his 
comparison  of  energy  to  amounts  of  money  values  deposited  in  a  bank  account. 
If  deposits  were  made  in  specie,  we  could  trace  every  dollar  of  a  deposit.  It 
is  true  we  can  not  do  so,  but  this  we  can  not  do  only  because  no  one  cares  to 
receive  definite  and  individual  coins,  but  is  satisfied  with  money  in  any  form. 
Therefore  the  bank  is  like  a  reservoir  of  water  which  receives  and  gives  out 
water  as  it  happens  to  come.  The  bank  gives  credit  for  amounts  received  and 
pays  out  amounts  according  to  request.  Thus  the  individual  coin  is  lost  sight 
of  as  the  many  drops  of  water  are  definite  and  concrete  masses,  and  every 
dollar  in  a  bank  represents  some  concrete  value  somewhere. 


564  THE  MONIST. 

of  definite  direction  and  of  definite  length.  Geometrical 
space  in  its  classical  Euclidean  form  is  not  stippled,  never- 
theless every  construction  is  particular.  Geometrical  points 
have  no  extension,  but  they  possess  a  definite  location,  be- 
ing determined,  e.  g.,  by  two  crossing  lines.  Thus  space  is 
not  the  totality  of  all  points,  but  the  totality  of  our  scope 
of  motion  and  anywhere  in  space  points  may  be  laid  down. 
In  a  word:  Time  and  geometrical  space  are  constructions 
invented  for  the  purpose  of  making  measurements  possible 
in  a  scope  of  potentialities. 

Actual  existence  is  always  definite,  pure  forms  however 
as  well  as  purely  formal  thoughts,  are  always  potential. 

It  seems  as  if  the  beginning  of  actuality  must  consist 
in  establishing  something  that  is  limited  and  concrete.  In 
this  way  it  appears  plausible  that  a  potential  world  would 
be  continuous  as  an  ocean  of  pure  ether  might  be,  but 
an  actual  world  ought  to  consist  of  a  group  of  units,  of 
atoms,  of  definite  particular  specks  of  existence  endowed 
with  definite  amounts  of  energy,  and  we  ought  to  be  able  to 
trace  every  definite  amount  of  existence  through  all  the 
changes  which  in  the  process  of  evolution  it  will  undergo; 
and  this  ought  to  be  true  as  regards  every  amount  of  both 
matter  and  energy. 

SOME  PHYSICAL  PROBLEMS  OF  RELATIVITY. 

The  physical  problems  presenting  themselves  in  the  ex- 
periments which  have  become  connected  with  the  move- 
ment of  relativity  do  not  seem  to  have  any  direct  bearing 
on  the  principle  of  relativity  itself.  Relations  are  of  a 
purely  formal  nature  and  relativity  therefore  belongs  to 
the  same  kind  of  knowledge  as  arithmetic,  geometry  and 
logic.  Relativity  can  and  must  be  applied  to  physics  just 
as  much  as  there  is  an  applied  mathematics,  but  as  the 
Pythagorean  theorem  is  independent  from  its  applications 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  565 

in  experience,  so  applied  relativity  can  neither  establish 
nor  refute  the  principle  of  relativity.  This  is  true  above  all 
of  the  well-known  and  most  important  Michelson-Morley 
experiment. 

The  instrument  made  in  Berlin  by  Schmidt  &  Haensch 
was  so  delicate  that  it  was  of  no  use  in  Berlin,  and  even 
when  placed  upon  the  foundation  for  the  pier  of  the  equa- 
torial in  the  Astrophysical  Observatory  at  Potsdam  the 
fringe  of  interference  rings  disappeared  by  stamping  upon 
the  pavement  at  a  distance  of  about  100  meters.  Every 
detail  of  consequence  was  taken  into  consideration,  not  only 
the  motion  of  the  earth  through  the  ether  but  also  the 
motion  of  the  whole  solar  system  towards  the  constellation 
of  Heracles.  The  expansion  of  the  brass  arms  of  the  in- 
strument through  a  change  in  temperature,  and  also  the 
bending  of  the  arms  through  rotation  were  duly  considered 
and  the  difficulties  arising  therefrom  met.  A  scale  ruled 
on  glass  was  employed  in  order  to  dispense  with  the  mi- 
crometer screw  which  here  proved  useless.  Yellow  light 
was  used,  because  its  wavelength  is  least  difficult  to  meas- 
ure. 

If  the  ether  is  at  rest  while  the  earth  moves  through 
it,  the  time  required  for  light  to  pass  from  one  point  to 
another  on  the  earth's  surface  would  depend  on  the  direc- 
tion in  which  it  travels.  Two  pencils  of  light  that  travel 
over  paths  at  right  angles  to  each  other  will  interfere;  the 
one  traveling  in  the  direction  of  the  earth's  motion  will 
travel  0.04  of  a  wave  length  farther  than  it  would  have 
done  were  the  earth  at  rest,  while  the  other  pencil  at  right 
angles  to  the  motion  of  the  earth  would  not  be  affected. 
The  results  of  Professor  Michelson's  experiment  are  neg- 
ative. He  found  very  small  displacements  in  the  fringes  of 
his  ray  of  light,  so  small  that  they  must  be  accounted  as 
mere  errors  of  the  experiment.  While  we  ought  to  expect 


566  THE  MONIST. 

a  displacement  of  0.05  we  have  only  such  as  lie  between 
0.004  and  0.015.  Professor  Michelson  says:11 

"The  interpretation  of  these  results  is  that  there  is  no 
displacement  of  the  interference  bands.  The  result  of  the 
hypothesis  of  a  stationary  ether  is  thus  shown  to  be  in- 
correct, and  the  necessary  conclusion  follows  that  the  hy- 
pothesis is  erroneous. 

"This  conclusion  directly  contradicts  the  explanation 
of  the  phenomenon  of  aberration  which  has  been  hitherto 
generally  accepted,  and  which  presupposes  that  the  earth 
moves  through  the  ether,  the  latter  remaining  at  rest." 

In  another  article  Professor  Michelson  states  his  re- 
sult thus:12 

"The  luminiferous  ether  is  entirely  unaffected  by  the 
motion  of  the  matter  which  it  permeates." 

Professor  Michelson  has  varied  the  conditions  of  his 
experiment  by  trying  whether  deviations  could  be  detected 
through  a  change  of  level,  by  throwing  pencils  of  light 
upward  and  by  repeating  it  at  different  hours  of  the  day, 
but  the  displacements  remained  insignificant.  One  of  Pro- 
fessor Michelson's  articles  ends  thus:13 

"In  any  case  we  are  driven  to  extraordinary  conclu- 
sions, and  the  choice  lies  between  these  three : 

"i.  The  earth  passes  through  the  ether  (or  rather  allows 
the  ether  to  pass  through  its  entire  mass)  without  appre- 
ciable influence. 

"2.  The  length  of  all  bodies  is  altered  (equally?)  by 
their  motion  through  the  ether.14 

n  "The  Relative  Motion  of  the  Earth  and  the  Luminiferous  Ether"  in  The 
American  Journal  of  Science,  Vol.  CXXII,  page  128. 

12  "Influence  of  Motion  of  the  Medium  on  the  Velocity  of  Light,"  in  The 
American  Journal  of  Science,  Vol.  CXXXI,  page  386. 

18  "The  Relative  Motion  of  the  Earth  and  the  Ether,"  The  American  Jour- 
nal of  Science,  Vol.  CLIII,  p.  478. 

14  This  would  be  the  case  according  to  the  theory  of  H.  A.  Lorentz,  whose 
views  are  mainly  presented  in  the  Encyclopadie  der  math.  Wissenschaften. 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  567 

"3.  The  earth  in  its  motion  drags  with  it  the  ether  even 
at  distances  of  many  thousand  kilometers  from  its  surface." 

Another  article  by  Professor  Michelson  on  the  same 
subject  is  published  in  The  American  Journal  of  Science, 
Vol.  CXXXIV,  p.  333- 

What  this  famous  experiment  has  to  do  with  the  prin- 
ciple of  relativity  except  in  a  most  general  way,  is  not  yet 
clear  to  those  who  have  not  joined  the  ranks  of  the  rela- 
tivity physicists;  but  the  relativity  physicists  insist  very 
vigorously  and  dogmatically  that  it  proves,  or  at  least 
favors,  their  theory.  Professor  Michelson  himself  has  not 
joined  their  ranks,  though  he  recognizes  the  difficulties 
of  the  situation. 

It  is  strange  that  Michelson's  experiment  seems  to 
stand  in  contradiction  to  another  and  older  experiment 
made  first  by  Bradley,  which  is  known  as  the  aberration 
of  light.  If  the  earth  passes  through  the  ether  with  its 
own  velocity  (e)  while  the  rays  of  the  sun  come  down 
upon  the  earth  with  the  velocity  of  light  (/)  there  ought 
to  be  a  deflection  of  light  amounting  to  e/l,  viz.,  the  veloc- 
ity of  the  earth  divided  by  the  velocity  of  the  light  in  its 
path  from  the  sun  towards  the  earth,  and  though  this  rela- 
tion is  very  small,  it  has  actually  been  observed  and  de- 
termined to  amount  to  a  trifle  over  twenty  seconds. 

This  conclusion  which  could  be  anticipated  according 
to  the  logic  of  mechanics  seems  to  be  contradicted  by 
Michelson-Morley's  experiment  in  which  the  attempt  is 
made  to  measure  with  a  ray  of  light  the  motion  of  the  earth 
while  passing  through  the  ether. 

The  discrepancy  between  the  two  experiments  will  per- 
haps find  a  proper  explanation  in  the  proposition  that  if 
the  source  of  light  lies  outside  the  earth  as  in  the  case 
of  the  rays  of  the  sun,  they  will  show  the  deflection.  As 
is  to  be  expected  they  would  come  down  in  straight  lines 
like  raindrops  falling  in  an  absolutely  quiet  air  which 


568  THE  MONIST. 

would  be  caught  by  a  moving  body  as  if  they  came  down 
at  an  angle;  but  if  the  source  of  light  moves  along  with 
the  earth  there  would  be  no  difference  whichever  way  they 
turn,  first  towards  the  east  or  first  towards  the  west,  or  at 
right  angles,  and  the  sources  of  the  light  would  partake  of 
the  acceleration  of  the  earth  so  as  to  show  no  difference, 
as  raindrops  dripping  down  within  the  car  would  fall  down 
in  straight  lines  from  its  top  to  the  floor,  assuming  that  the 
doors  and  windows  of  the  car  are  hermetically  closed  and 
there  be  no  draft  which  would  deflect  their  perpendicular 
dripping. 

It  almost  seems  as  if  some  ether  were  carried  along 
by  the  earth  to  a  considerable  distance  beyond  its  sur- 
face while  the  other  ether  in  outer  space  would  remain  at 
rest,  but  it  would  be  bold  for  any  one  but  a  specialist  to 
venture  the  proposition  of  any  theory  on  so  new  a  subject 
of  which  few  facts  only  have  been  ascertained.  Yet  most 
assuredly  the  topic  under  investigation  has  nothing  to  do 
with  the  principle  of  relativity,  unless  relativity  is  a  mis- 
nomer for  the  phenomena  attributed  to  the  luminiferous 
ether. 

The  question  of  relativity  is  a  philosophical  problem, 
but  the  Michelson-Morley  experiment  is  of  a  purely  phys- 
ical nature,  and  so  we  must  expect  that  the  last  word  as 
to  its  explanation  should  be  given  by  physicists. 

The  other  experiment  which  is  assumed  to  verify  the 
principle  of  relativity  is  the  one  first  made  by  Kauffmann, 
and  afterwards  repeated  in  a  modified  form  by  Bucherer. 
This  experiment  too  has  little  or  nothing  to  do  with  rela- 
tivity. On  the  contrary  it  seems  to  prove  the  existence  of 
something  absolute  for  it  reaches  a  limit  of  velocity. 

There  is  at  present  a  tendency  in  the  world  of  thought, 
noticeable  in  pragmatism  and  other  anti-intellectual  move- 
ments, which  seems  to  annihilate  the  very  existence  of 
objectivity,  and  with  it  science,  man's  endeavor  after  a 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  569 

purely  objective  cognition.  Everything  is  relative,  and  the 
general  belief  has  spread  that  an  absolutely  objective  de- 
scription is  impossible.  To  speak  of  the  size  of  objects 
seems  to  have  lost  its  sense,  for  size  has  become  to  the 
present  generation  merely  the  result  of  measurement,  and 
thus  an  objective  determination  is  in  some  quarters  looked 
upon  as  a  superstition  of  prescientific  tradition,  an  inheri- 
tance from  the  dark  ages.  But  it  is  not  true  that  there  is 
no  objectivity,  for  one  of  the  greatest  accomplishments  of 
Michelson  was  the  establishment  of  a  definite  measure  by 
calculating  the  size  of  a  meter  in  wave-lengths  or  red 
cadmium  light  in  a  vacuum.  The  waves  of  light  are  ab- 
solutely definite,  and  thus  we  have  here  a  result  of  measure- 
ment in  truly  objective  terms.  If  the  Kauffmann-Bucherer 
experiments  prove,  as  is  claimed,  that  an  increase  of  veloc- 
ity means  an  increase  of  mass  and  that  the  limit  which  is 
reached  is  the  velocity  of  light,  we  only  learn  that  rela- 
tivity is  not  without  bounds,  and  that  on  the  contrary  a 
climax  is  reached  which  can  not  be  surpassed.  The  high- 
est velocity  is  the  velocity  of  light. 

The  conclusion  that  the  highest  velocity  is  the  velocity 
of  light  seems  to  be  contradicted  by  the  facts  of  gravitation 
for  according  to  the  Newtonian  theory  gravitation  is  pos- 
sessed of  a  practically  infinite  velocity  in  that  the  gravity 
of  the  sun  exercises  its  influence  upon  the  planets  without 
any  perceptible  difference  of  time.  But  this  is  no  object- 
tion,  for  consider :  The  action  of  gravity  formulated  in  the 
well-known  law  of  falling  bodies  and  of  their  acceleration 
which  describes  true  motions  is  very  slow  in  comparison 
to  the  velocity  of  light.  The  influence  which  is  exercised 
in  the  strain  between  two  gravitating  bodies,  say  between 
the  moon  and  the  earth,  is  not  a  motion  at  all,  but  a  con- 
dition, and  this  condition  is  the  same  between  the  two  cen- 
ters of  the  thus  interrelated  bodies.  It  is  a  state  of  tension 
and  there  is  no  transference  of  a  wave  motion  either  from 


57O  THE  MONIST. 

the  moon  to  the  earth  or  from  the  earth  to  the  moon.  The 
tension  is  simultaneous.  The  misconception  seems  to  rise 
from  the  error  that  there  are  two  bodies  and  there  is  a 
third  item  which  manifests  itself  as  a  passing  from  the 
one  to  the  other  under  the  name  of  gravitation.  We  must 
view  the  whole  system  as  one  field  of  action  in  which  sev- 
eral bodies  in  motion  are  balanced  among  themselves  ac- 
cording to  their  mass.  Their  mutual  attraction  is  not 
transferred  motion  but  a  simultaneous  interaction.  New- 
ton retarded  the  general  acceptance  of  the  law  of  gravita- 
tion, first  definitely  proposed  by  Hooke,  for  eighteen  long 
years  because  he  could  not  make  up  his  mind  to  believe  in 
an  actio  in  distans,  and  when  he  was  finally  convinced,  he 
still  expressed  his  misgivings  how  to  overcome  this  objec- 
tion, but  is  there  any  actio  in  distans  at  all?  Is  not  the 
whole  system  of  the  universe  an  interrelated  whole  and 
does  not  a  center  of  gravity  (howsoever  it  may  have  origi- 
nated) extend  so  far  as  its  stress  reaches?  Where  its 
strain  produces  a  tension,  there  it  affects  its  surround- 
ings. If  we  look  upon  the  phenomena  of  gravitation  in 
this  light  we  need  not  make  the  fantastical  assumption 
that  gravity  is  possessed  of  an  infinite  velocity. 

The  relation  between  the  increase  of  velocity  and  the 
increase  of  mass  promises  to  throw  light  on  the  ultimate 
constitution  of  matter,  but  the  result  of  the  experiment 
is  only  the  first  step  to  a  solution  of  this  tremendous  prob- 
lem, concerning  which  at  the  present  stage  of  science  we 
can  have  only  vague  suggestions.  When  the  man  appears 
who  can  read  the  facts  aright,  he  may  be  able  to  point  out 
how  by  a  mere  stress  the  aboriginal  world-stuff  which, 
for  all  we  know,  may  be,  or  even  must  be,  the  ether,  pro- 
duces a  tension  within  this  mysterious  infinitely  elastic 
and  incredibly  thin  substance,  and  the  tension  between  two 
centers  of  such  contraction  would,  like  the  strain  between 
nodes  within  thin  tridimensional  rubber,  act  in  all  direc- 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  571 

tions  according  to  the  Newtonian  formula  of  gravitation,  as 
being  directly  proportional  to  the  product  of  their  amounts 
of  contraction,  and  inversely  proportional  to  the  square 
of  their  distance  between  two  centers.  Thus  the  origin  of 
matter  would  be  due  to  an  unknown  force  which  with  a 
velocity  only  inferior  to  the  velocity  of  light  would  drive 
infinitely  small  corpuscles  around  in  a  whirling  dance  with 
such  a  regulated  speed  that  conglomerated  multitudes  of 
such  whirls  would  appear  to  us  as  solid  masses. 

Here  again  we  would  be  confronted  by  an  ultimate 
limit.  We  would  discover  that  objective  reality,  our  world 
of  matter  in  motion,  is  built  up  of  ultimate  particles;  or 
perhaps  better,  of  ultimate  activities,  that  below  the  atom 
there  are  smaller  units,  the  hypothetical  electrons,  which 
may  be  characterized  as  centers  of  force,  and  that  they  are 
due  to  condensation  which  produces  the  phenomena  of 
gravitation.  All  further  phenomena  of  physics  and  chem- 
istry would  have  to  be  explained  as  the  result  of  these  ele- 
mentary actions. 

Formerly  thinkers  were  inclined  to  see  infinity  all 
around.  They  thought  of  the  atomic  structure  not  only 
as  infinitesimally  small,  but  also  as  truly  infinite ;  the  mole- 
cules being  analyzable  into  atoms  and  the  atoms  again 
into  still  smaller  units,  say  into  electrons  or  monads,  and 
that  the  monads  were  again  compounds  of  monadules  and 
so  forth — all  this  being  argued  on  the  poetic  notion  that 

"Great  fleas  have  little  fleas 
Upon  their  backs  to  bite  'em, 
And  little  fleas  have  lesser  fleas, 
And  so  ad  infinitum" 

The  molecule  is  a  kind  of  planetary  system,  with  atoms 
as  satellites,  so  is  the  atom  with  its  circling  electrons ;  why 
should  not  the  electron  be  of  the  same  construction  and 
why  should  not  the  component  parts  of  the  electron  be  as- 
sumed to  be  made  after  the  same  pattern  world  without 


572 


THE  MONIST. 


end?  On  the  other  hand  our  solar  system  is  one  among 
uncountably  many  others  of  the  Milky  Way;  and  the 
Milky  Way  in  its  turn  is  one  universe  of  an  enormously 
larger  system  of  many  Milky  Ways.  This  is  the  conclu- 
sion which  astronomy  has  deduced  from  actual  facts.  Why 
then  should  not  this  in  our  opinion  enormous  system  of  the 
many  Milky  Ways  be  only  a  tiny  item  in  a  still  larger  sys- 
tem, and  why  should  we  not  be  justified  in  the  assumption 
that  we  are  confronted  with  an  infinite  vista  into  both 
directions  toward  the  infinitely  small  and  the  infinitely 
great? 

This  notion  has  been  brought  out  in  the  second  quatrain 
which  reads: 

"And  the  great  fleas  themselves  in  turn 
Have  greater  fleas  to  go  on, 
While  these  again  have  greater  still, 
And  greater  still  and  so  on." 

A  vista  into  infinitudes,  going  out  into  the  infinitely 
small  and  the  infinitely  great,  now  seems  to  become  un- 
tenable, and  definite  limits  loom  up,  which  condition,  so  it 
seems  to  us,  would  reveal,  not  a  bottomless  and  undefinable 
relativity  but  a  definite  world  of  an  objective  reality  with 
definite  interrelations  and  limits.  If  there  are  definite  limits 
in  either  direction  we  may  fairly  well  assume  that  they  are 
in  both  directions.  Further,  if  the  universe  is  definite  in 
its  space  relation,  it  should  also  be  definitely  limited  in 
time.  The  world  may  have  originated  in  an  immeasurable 
ocean  of  uniformities  as  a  definite  commotion  and  may 
terminate  again  in  a  general  dissolution  by  dissipation. 
If  such  be  the  case  the  relativity  principle  would  not  apply 
to  the  whole.  Relativity  would  mean  the  interrelationship 
of  all  things,  but  the  whole  as  a  whole  would  be  of  a 
definite  particularity  with  definite  boundaries  while  the  con- 
stitution of  the  world  would  exhibit  a  structure  of  ex- 
tremely tiny  ultimate  units  of  a  determinably  definite  size, 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  573 

endowed  with  a  definite  velocity  and  at  every  given  point 
of  a  definite  form  of  motion. 

While  the  totality  of  existence,  the  sum  total  of  our 
Milky  Ways,  appears  to  have  had  a  beginning  and  may 
after  the  lapse  of  immeasurable  ages  come  again  to  an 
end,  we  do  not  deem  it  excluded  that  the  same  process 
of  world-formation  may  start  again,  as  it  probably  was 
repeated  long  before  the  origin  of  this  our  present  uni- 
verse. While  thus  everything  existent,  even  the  ether  it- 
self in  its  totality,  would  have  to  be  regarded  as  particular 
and  concrete  with  definite  boundaries  and  as  being  limited 
to  a  definite  time  both  in  its  beginning  and  in  its  end,  there 
would  after  all  loom  up  in  the  background  of  this  world  an 
infinitude  of  space,  an  eternity  of  time  and  an  unfathom- 
able wealth  of  potentialities  as  to  new  formations  which  in 
spite  of  all  the  light  which  the  most  advanced  science  will 
ever  shed  on  the  world  problem  will  keep  this  great  All  of 
existence  with  its  inexhaustible  resources  and  its  myste- 
rious order  an  object  of  constant  \vonder  and  awe. 

The  relativity  problem  as  such  is  a  philosophical  prob- 
lem, but  the  relativity  physicists  have  made  a  physical 
problem  of  it,  and  the  philosophical  problem  of  relativity 
is  not  a  new  problem,  it  is  as  old  as  science ;  it  is  only  the 
lack  of  philosophical  training  which  has  led  to  the  enun- 
ciation of  some  baffling  paradoxes  which  if  they  were  true 
would  make  objective  science  impossible,  for  they  would 
abolish  definiteness  of  any  kind  and  do  away  with  objectiv- 
ity. And  strange  to  say,  claims  of  this  kind  are  upheld  on  the 
ground  of  experiments  which  tend  to  establish  the  exist- 
ence of  an  absolute,  or  as  we  would  prefer  to  say,  of  some 
ultimate,  which  would  prove  that  our  experience  does  not 
float  as  a  local  tangle  in  an  endless  infinitude,  but  that 
there  is  a  beginning  and  end,  and  also  a  boundary  of  all 
concrete  reality  at  every  definitely  given  moment.  No  mys- 
ticism is  needed.  Infinitude  and  eternality  are  potential- 


574  THE  MONIST. 

ities,  not  actualities.  They  are  vistas  of  what  may  be,  not 
what  is.  They  constitute  the  inexhaustible  wealth  of  na- 
ture and  of  life  without  robbing  science  of  its  validity. 

There  is  a  tendency  in  mankind  to  think  of  the  present 
moment  as  the  climax  of  the  past,  which  ushers  in  a  new  era 
by  being  an  unprecedented  and  unique  start.  Every  new 
generation  passes  through  such  a  period  of  self-sufficiency 
and  of  an  intoxication  with  their  own  incomparable  self- 
hood. The  old  problems  seem  new  to  them,  and  trying  to 
formulate  them  in  an  original  way,  they  applaud  their  own 
mistakes  as  something  extraordinary  and  wonderful. 
Goethe  characterizes  this  tendency  in  the  young  graduate 
who  has  just  taken  his  degree  of  Bachelor  (See  Faust, 
Second  Part,  Act  II)  where  this  young  man  vents  his  am- 
bitious conceit  in  these  words: 

"This  is  Youth's  noblest  calling  and  most  fit! 
The  world  was  not,  ere  I  created  it; 
The  sun  I  drew  from  out  the  orient  sea; 
The  moon  began  her  changeful  course  with  me ; 
The  Day  put  on  her  shining  robes,  to  greet  me ; 
The  Earth  grew  green,  and  burst  in  flower  to  meet  me, 
And  when  I  beckoned,  from  the  primal  night 
The  stars  unveiled  their  splendors  to  my  sight. 
Who,  save  myself,  to  you  deliverance  brought 
From  commonplaces  of  restricted  thought? 
I,  proud  and  free,  even  as  dictates  my  mind, 
Follow  with  joy  the  inward  light  I  find, 
And  speed  along,  in  mine  own  ecstasy, 
Darkness  behind,  and  Glory  leading  me!" 

It  is  apparent  that  the  relativity  physicists  confront  an 
important  problem,  but  they  have  not  succeeded  in  solving 
it ;  they  have  not  even  as  yet  properly  formulated  the  ques- 
tion and  their  propositions  are  still  in  a  state  of  fermen- 
tation. It  is  difficult  to  say  what  will  come  of  it.  It  is  to 
be  hoped,  however,  that  the  movement  will  follow  the  usual 
course  of  mental  growth.  The  relativists  will  drop  their 
extravagant  claims,  they  will  mature  the  truth  which  they 
grope  after  and  will  at  last  formulate  it  into  clear  state- 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  575 

ments  so  as  to  justify  the  prophecy  of  Mephistopheles, 
who  comments  upon  the  proud  words  of  the  young  Bach- 
elor thus : 

"Go  hence,  magnificent  Original ! — 
What  grief  on  thee  would  insight  cast ! 
Who  can  think  wise  or  stupid  things  at  all, 
That  were  not  thought  already  in  the  Past? 
Yet  even  from  him  we're  not  in  special  peril ; 
He  will,  ere  long,  to  other  thoughts  incline : 
The  must  may  foam  absurdly  in  the  barrel, 
Nathless  it  turns  at  last  to  wine." 

At  the  present  state  of  our  knowledge  it  would  be  fan- 
tastical to  suggest  a  solution  of  the  physical  problems  con- 
nected with  the  relativity  movement,  and  we  must  leave 
the  discussion  of  them  to  the  future,  for  ere  we  can  ap- 
proach a  solution  we  must  know  much  more  about  the 
ultimate  constituents  of  matter. 

Who  will  furnish  the  key  to  the  lock  of  the  closed  door 
at  which  the  relativity  physicists  are  knocking? 

CONCLUSION. 

The  details  of  the  physical  problems  and  their  solution 
have  only  a  slight  interest  for  philosophy.  The  philosopher, 
however,  expects  that  the  physicist's  solutions  shall  be  con- 
sistent and  that  our  scientific  world-conception  shall  tol- 
erate no  contradictions. 

If  we  consider  the  all-importance  of  form  and  the 
enormous  significance  which  the  formal  sciences  possess,  we 
are  inclined  to  regard  the  philosophy  of  relativity  as  a 
synonym  and  parallel  development  of  the  philosophy  of 
science  —  the  philosophy  of  form.  But  before  we  can 
definitely  say  so,  we  would  expect  the  relativists  to  work 
out  their  philosophical  substructure  in  a  conservative  way, 
to  rid  themselves  of  their  paradoxical  propositions,  give  up 
false  pretensions  to  originality,  recognize  the  past  tradi- 
tions of  science,  and  rather  than  abandon  the  past,  join 


576  THE  MONIST. 

their  cause  to  the  legitimate  progress  that  follows  from 
the  tendencies,  the  ideals  and  aspirations  of  the  established 
sciences. 

We  do  not  deny  the  relativity  of  all  existence  through- 
out and  without  exception,  but  we  still  cling  to  the  old 
scientific  ideal  of  objectivity  and  we  can  not  see  that  the 
relativity  principle  is  well  established. 

The  great  question  before  the  world  of  thinkers  is  this : 
Is  it  possible  to  construct  a  philosophy  of  science?  The 
author  of  this  essay  has  answered  this  question  in  the  affir- 
mative, and  has  worked  in  this  field  for  fully  a  quarter  of 
a  century.  He  has  worked  out  the  details  of  a  philosophy 
of  science,  and  has  submitted  to  the  world  in  both  The 
Open  Court  and  The  Monist  his  answers  to  the  several 
philosophical  questions.  These  questions  are:  the  nature 
of  the  soul ;  the  origin  of  sentiency  and  of  thought ;  the  na- 
ture of  reason,  especially  in  its  origin  and  in  its  relation 
to  language,  the  mechanism  with  which  reason  manifests 
itself;  the  nature  of  ethics  and  the  foundation  of  morality 
as  it  is  found  in  the  laws  of  the  objective  world;  the  sig- 
nificance of  the  God-conception  as  the  authority  of  conduct, 
as  the  ideal  of  right  and  wrong,  as  the  standard  of  truth 
and  error,  as  the  object  of  devotion,  of  gratitude,  of  rev- 
erence mainly  as  the  factor  which  determines  good  and 
evil.  All  these  questions  are  not  beyond  the  scope  of  scien- 
tific inquiry  and  in  the  philosophy  of  science  definite  solu- 
tions are  propounded  which,  though  based  on  radical  prin- 
ciples of  unbiased  thought,  lead  to  a  justification  of  the 
historical  growth  of  religion  and  science. 

The  whole  scope  of  existence  as  it  presents  itself  in 
human  experience  can  become  an  object  of  scientific  in- 
quiry, and  all  scientific  problems  admit  ultimately  of  a  defi- 
nite solution  without  equivocation  or  prevarication,  yet 
at  the  same  time  science  is  only  one  attitude  among  several 
others  from  which  the  world  can  be  confronted.  The  noetic 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  577 

conception  is  the  ideal  of  understanding  the  world  in  its 
pure  objectivity  represented  in  mental  terms  to  the  exclu- 
sion of  sentimental  subjectivity.  But  man  is  not  a  child 
of  reason  only.  He  is  also  endowed  with  sentiments,  with 
will  and  with  artistic  tendencies.  While  the  scientific 
world-conception  is  absolutely  indispensable  for  the  man 
of  thought  who  works  for  a  constant  elevation  of  mankind 
upon  a  higher  level,  we  must  at  the  same  time  recognize 
the  rights  of  the  large  masses  who  naturally  are  non- 
scientific  and  are  swayed  by  sentiment,  by  devotion,  by  art, 
by  ethical  aspirations,  by  a  religious  comprehension  of  life ; 
and  thus  we  see  in  artistic  and  religious  conceptions  ways 
of  treating  the  world  problem  which  are  by  no  means  un- 
justified and  ought  not  to  be  repudiated  on  the  ground  that 
they  are  non-scientific,  sometimes  unscientific,  or  even  anti- 
scientific  and  purely  sentimental.  Religious  cosmogonies, 
ecclesiastical  ceremonies,  religio  -  poetical  fictions  possess 
values  of  their  own  which  can  not  and  should  not  be  meas- 
ured by  the  standards  of  scientific  method.  The  mystic 
also  has  his  right  to  confront  the  world  with  his  emotions 
and  visions.  Nevertheless,  even  here  the  philosophy  of 
science  will  be  capable  of  investigating  various  products 
of  these  tendencies  and  has  a  right  to  evaluate  their  truth 
or  untruth  by  tracing  the  meaning  of  allegorical  poetry 
as  well  as  the  wholesomeness  of  ethical  attitudes  which  they 
encourage.  In  this  way  the  philosophy  of  science  as  worked 
out  by  the  present  writer  has  by  no  means  been  narrow  but 
has  granted  a  free  scope  to  all  legitimate  tendencies  of  the 
human  mind,  and  if  the  philosophy  of  science  has  been 
properly  understood,  leaders  of  thought  in  the  movements  of 
pragmatism,  relativism,  Bergsonianism  and  other  modern 
tendencies,  would  have  been  able  to  avoid  at  least  some  of 
their  aberrations,  and  could  have  devoted  their  energies  to 
efforts  in  the  right  direction.  At  any  rate  they  would  have 
been  better  understood;  instead  of  being  classified  with 


578  THE  MONIST. 

philosophy,  they  would  more  properly  have  been  regarded 
as  a  new  species  of  poetry,  or  as  literary  ebullitions.  Such 
they  are ;  as  such  they  possess  value.  They  are  not  philos- 
ophy, certainly  not  philosophy  in  the  strict  sense  of  the 
word;  they  are  not  scientific  world-conceptions. 

It  may  appear  strange  to  class  the  movement  which 
proclaims  the  principle  of  relativity  in  the  same  category 
with  pragmatism  and  other  antiscientific  tendencies.  We 
do  so  because  the  relativists  have  much  in  common  with 
pragmatists,  because  both  cancel  the  ideal  of  objectivity, 
both  identify  truth  with  the  subjective  conception  of  the 
real  or  with  the  observer's  statement  of  facts.  They  iden- 
tify size  with  result  of  measurement  and  think  that  the 
traditional  view  of  truth  is  an  error. 

We  do  not  overlook  the  fact  that  the  relativists  are  of 
a  highly  intellectual  type  and  employ  scientific  methods, 
but  their  aim  is  after  all  a  denial  of  the  old  ideal  of  science, 
of  the  objectivity  of  truth,  and  of  clearness  of  thought.  All 
this  is  surrendered  for  the  sake  of  a  purely  subjective  simpli- 
fication of  statement  which  recommends  itself  in  their  own 
specialty.  Certainly  there  is  a  great  difference  between 
relativists  and  pragmatists,  but  we  recognize  in  both  a 
subjectivist  tendency  and  a  subjectivist  aim.  Neither  of 
them  feel  the  need  of  approximating  objectivity  and  both 
indulge  in  ideal  constructions,  both  build  air  castles,  the 
former  of  mathematical  fiction,  the  latter  of  philosophical 
poetry. 

All  these  modern  anti-scientific  isms  may  have  origi- 
nated through  the  one-sided  tendencies  of  a  misapplied 
scientism  or  even  through  the  lack  of  comprehension  of  the 
principles  and  the  significance  of  science  among  naturalists. 
These  isms  emphasize  therefore  certain  contentions  which 
have  a  nucleus  of  truth,  by  insisting  on  the  rights  of  senti- 
ment though  they  go  too  far  when  attacking  science  itself 


THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  RELATIVITY.  579 

and  claiming  a  superiority  for  unscientific  sentiment  over 
clear  and  methodical  thought. 

There  is  no  question  that  all  these  modern  movements 
try  each  in  its  own  way  to  satisfy  legitimate  tendencies,  but 
in  doing  so  they  have  mostly  gone  astray ;  partly  they  mis- 
understand their  own  aspirations,  partly  they  lack  sufficient 
depth  of  comprehension  and  width  of  horizon  in  encom- 
passing the  whole  realm  of  human  endeavor. 

We  do  not  expect  that  in  this  partisan  scramble  of  var- 
ious prejudices,  the  whole  world  of  thinkers  can  be  induced 
to  recognize  the  common  ideal  of  philosophical  thought, 
but  we  hope  that  there  will  be  enough  minds  to  understand 
the  several  movements,  to  appreciate  them  so  far  as  their 
aspirations  are  legitimate,  and  to  discover  their  weak  points 
in  which  they  stray  away  from  the  straight  path  that  leads 
forward  to  a  truer,  deeper  and  a  broader  conception  of  the 
world. 

EDITOR. 


ATOMIC  THEORIES  OF  ENERGY. 

A  THEORY  involving  some  sort  of  a  discrete  or  dis- 
continuous structure  of  energy  has  been  put  forward 
by  Prof.  Max  Planck  of  the  University  of  Berlin.  The 
various  aspects  of  this  theory  are  discussed  and  elaborated 
by  the  late  M.  Henri  Poincare  in  a  paper  entitled  "L'Hypo- 
these  des  Quanta,"  published  in  the  Revue  Scientifique 
(Paris,  Feb.  21,  1912). 

A  paper  in  which  a  discontinuous  or  "atomic"  struc- 
ture of  energy  was  suggested  was  prepared  by  the  present 
writer  fifteen  years  ago  but  remains  unpublished  for  rea- 
sons that  will  appear  later.  Although  he  has  no  desire  to 
put  in  a  claim  of  priority  and  is  well  aware  that  failure  to 
publish  would  put  any  such  claim  out  of  court,  it  seems  to 
him  that  in  connection  with  present  radical  developments 
in  physical  theory  the  paper,  together  with  some  correspon- 
dence relating  thereto,  has  historical  interest.  Planck's 
theory  was  suggested  by  thermodynamical  considerations. 
In  the  paper  now  to  be  quoted  the  matter  was  approached 
from  the  standpoint  of  a  criterion  for  determining  the  iden- 
tity of  two  portions  of  matter  or  of  energy.  The  paper  is 
as  follows : 

SOME  CONSIDERATIONS  ON  THE  IDENTITY  OF  DEFINITE  POR- 
TIONS OF  ENERGY. 

It  has  been  remarked  recently  that  physicists  are  now 
divided  into  two  opposing  schools  according  to  the  way  in 


ATOMIC  THEORIES  OF  ENERGY.  581 

which  they  view  the  subject  of  energy,  some  regarding  it 
as  a  mere  mathematical  abstraction  and  others  looking 
upon  it  as  a  physical  entity,  filling  space  and  continuously 
migrating  by  definite  paths  from  one  place  to  another.  It 
may  be  added  that  there  are  numerous  factions  within 
these  two  parties;  for  instance,  not  all  of  those  who  con- 
sider energy  to  be  something  more  than  a  mere  mathemat- 
ical expression  would  maintain  that  a  given  quantity  of  it 
retains  its  identity  just  as  a  given  quantity  of  matter  does. 
In  fact  a  close  analysis  would  possibly  show  that  opinions 
are  graded  very  closely  and  continuously  from  a  view 
hardly  differing  from  that  of  Lagrange,  who  clearly  saw 
and  freely  used  the  mathematical  considerations  involving 
energy  before  the  word  had  been  invented  or  its  physical 
meaning  developed,  up  to  that  stated  recently  in  its  ex- 
treme form  by  Professor  Ostwald,  who  would  replace  what 
he  terms  a  mechanical  theory  of  the  universe  by  an  "ener- 
getical" theory,  and  would  dwell  exclusively  on  energy  as 
opposed  to  its  vehicles. 

Differences  of  opinion  of  this  sort  very  frequently  re- 
duce to  differences  of  definition,  and  in  this  case  the  mean- 
ing of  the  word  "identity"  or  some  similar  word  or  phrase 
has  undoubtedly  much  to  do  with  the  view  that  is  taken 
of  the  matter.  It  may  be  interesting,  for  instance,  to  look 
for  a  moment  at  our  ideas  of  the  identity  of  matter  and  the 
extent  to  which  they  are  influenced  by  the  accepted  theory 
of  its  constitution. 

Very  few  persons  would  hesitate  to  admit  that  the 
matter  that  now  constitutes  the  universe  is  identical  in 
amount  with  that  which  constituted  it  one  million  years 
ago,  and  that  any  given  portion  of  that  matter  is  identical 
with  an  equal  amount  of  matter  that  then  existed,  although 
the  situations  of  the  parts  of  that  portion  might  be  and 
probably  were  widely  different  in  the  two  cases.  To  assert 
this  is  of  course  a  very  different  thing  from  asserting  that 


THE  MONIST. 

the  identity  of  the  two  portions  or  any  parts  thereof  could 
have  been  practically  shown  by  following  them  during  all 
their  changes  of  location  or  state.  That  cannot  be  done 
even  in  the  case  of  some  simple  changes  that  are  effected 
in  a  fraction  of  a  second.  For  instance,  if  water  from  the 
pail  A  be  mixed  with  water  from  the  pail  B  there  is  no 
possible  way  of  telling  which  pail  any  given  portion  of  the 
mixture  came  from  or  in  what  proportions,  yet  it  is  certain 
that  such  portion  is  identical  with  a  portion  of  equal  mass 
that  recently  occupied  part  of  one  or  both  pails. 

How  far  our  certainty  as  to  this  is  influenced  by  our 
ideas  regarding  the  ultimate  constitution  of  the  water  is 
worthy  of  investigation.  All  who  accept  the  molecular 
theory,  for  instance,  will  regard  our  inability  to  trace  the 
elements  of  a  mixture  as  due  to  purely  physical  limitations. 
A  set  of  Maxwell's  "demons"  if  bidden  to  watch  the  mole- 
cules of  the  water  in  pail  A,  one  demon  being  assigned  to 
each  molecule,  would  be  able  to  tell  us  at  any  time  the  pre- 
cise proportions  of  any  given  part  of  the  mixture.  But  if 
we  should  not  accept  the  molecular  theory  and  believe  for 
instance,  that  water  is  a  continuum,  absolutely  homogene- 
ous, no  matter  how  small  portions  of  it  be  selected,  then 
our  demons  would  be  as  powerless  as  we  ourselves  now 
are  to  trace. the  constituents  in  the  mixture. 

We  are  now  in  a  position  to  ask  the  question:  Is  the 
matter  in  a  mixture  of  two  continua  identical  with  that  of 
its  constituents  ?  The  identity  certainly  seems  of  a  different 
kind  or  degree  from  that  which  obtains  in  the  first  case, 
for  there  is  no  part,  however  small,  that  was  derived  from 
one  pail  alone.  The  mixture  is  something  more  than  a 
mere  juxtaposition  of  elements  each  of  which  has  retained 
its  identity;  it  is  now  of  such  nature  that  no  part  of  it  is 
identical  with  any  part  of  A  alone  or  of  B  alone,  nor  of 
A+B,  where  the  sign  +  denotes  simple  juxtaposition.  It 
is  identical,  to  be  sure,  with  a  perfect  mixture  of  certain 


ATOMIC  THEORIES  OF  ENERGY.  583 

parts  of  A  and  B,  but  this  is  simply  saying  that  it  is  iden- 
tical with  what  it  is  now,  that  is,  with  itself,  not  with  some- 
thing that  went  before. 

Probably  no  one  now  believes  that  water  or  any  other 
kind  of  matter  is  a  continuum,  but  the  bearing  of  what  has 
been  said  may  be  seen  when  we  remember  that  this  is  pre- 
cisely the  present  stage  of  our  belief  regarding  energy. 

No  one,  so  far  as  I  know,  has  ventured  to  suggest  what 
may  be  termed  a  molecular  theory  of  energy,  a  somewhat 
remarkable  fact  when  we  consider  the  control  now  exer- 
cised over  all  thought  in  physics  by  molecular  theories  of 
matter.  While  we  now  believe,  for  instance,  that  a  material 
body,  say  a  crystal,  can  by  no  possibility  increase  continu- 
ously in  mass,  but  must  do  so  step  by  step,  the  minimum 
mass  of  matter  that  can  be  added  being  the  molecule,  we 
believe  on  the  contrary  that  the  energy  possessed  by  the 
same  body  can  and  may  increase  with  absolutely  perfect 
continuity,  being  hampered  by  no  such  restriction. 

It  is  not  the  purpose  of  this  paper  to  discuss  whether 
we  have  grounds  for  belief  that  there  is  such  a  thing  as  a 
minimum  quantity,  or  atom,  of  energy,  that  does  not  sep- 
arate into  smaller  parts,  no  matter  what  changes  it  under- 
goes. Suffice  it  to  say  that  there  appears  to  be  no  a  priori 
absurdity  in  such  an  idea.  At  first  sight  both  matter  and 
energy  appear  non-molecular  in  structure.  But  we  have 
been  forced  to  look  upon  the  gradual  growth  of  a  crystal 
as  a  step-by-step  process,  and  we  may  some  day,  by  equally 
cogent  considerations,  be  forced  to  regard  the  gradual  in- 
crease of  energy  of  an  accelerating  body  as  also  a  step-by- 
step  process,  although  the  discontinuity  is  as  invisible  to 
the  eye  in  the  latter  case  as  in  the  former. 

Without  following  this  out  any  farther,  however,  the 
point  may  be  here  emphasized  that  it  is  hardly  possible  for 
one  who,  like  the  majority  of  physicists,  regards  matter  as 
molecular  and  energy  as  a  continuum,  to  hold  the  same 


584  THE  MONIST. 

ideas  regarding  the  identity  of  the  two.  Efforts  to  show 
that  definite  portions  of  energy,  like  definite  portions  of 
matter,  retain  their  identity  have  hitherto  been  made  chiefly 
on  the  lines  of  a  demonstration  that  energy  travels  by  defi- 
nite and  continuous  paths  in  space  just  as  matter  does. 
This  is  very  well,  but  it  would  appear  to  be  necessary  to 
supplement  it  with  evidence  to  show  that  the  lines  repre- 
senting these  paths  do  not  form  at  their  intersections  con- 
tinuous blurs  that  not  only  forbid  any  practical  attempt  at 
identification  on  emergence,  but  make  it  doubtful  whether 
we  can  in  any  true  sense  call  the  issuing  path  identical  with 
the  entering  one.  Otherwise  the  identity  of  energy  can  be 
admitted  to  be  only  that  kind  of  identity  that  could  be  pre- 
served by  matter  if  its  molecular  structure  did  not  exist. 
One  who  can  admit  that  this  sort  of  identity  is  the  same 
sort  that  can  be  preserved  by  molecular  matter  may  be  able 
to  hold  the  identity  of  energy  in  the  present  state  of  the 
evidence,  but  the  present  attitude  of  physicists  would  seem 
to  show  that,  whether  they  realize  the  connection  of  the 
two  subjects  or  not,  they  cannot  take  this  view.  In  other 
words,  modern  views  of  the  identity  of  matter  seem  closely 
connected  with  modern  views  of  its  structure,  and  the  same 
connection  will  doubtless  hold  good  for  energy. 

Regarding  the  probable  success  of  an  attempt  to  prove 
that  energy  has  a  "structure"  analogous  to  the  molecular 
structure  of  matter,  any  prediction  would  doubtless  be  rash 
just  now.  The  writer  has  been  unable,  up  to  the  present 
time,  to  disprove  the  proposition,  but  the  subject  is  one  of 
corresponding  importance  to  that  of  the  whole  molecular 
theory  of  matter  and  should  not  be  entered  upon  lightly. 


The  writer  freely  acknowledges  at  present  that  the 
illustrations  in  the  foregoing  are  badly  chosen  and  some  of 
the  statements  are  too  strong,  but  it  still  represents  essen- 


ATOMIC  THEORIES  OF  ENERGY.  585 

tially  his  ideas  on  the  subject.  No  reputable  scientific  jour- 
nal would  undertake  to  publish  it.  The  paper  was  then 
sent  to  Prof.  J.  Willard  Gibbs  of  Yale,  and  elicited  the 
following  letter  from  him: 

"NEW  HAVEN,  June  2/97. 
"My  DEAR  MR.  BOSTWICK  : 

"I  regret  that  I  have  allowed  your  letter  to  lie  so  long 
unanswered.  It  was  in  fact  not  very  easy  to  answer,  and 
when  one  lays  a  letter  aside  to  answer,  the  weeks  slip  away 
very  fast. 

"I  do  not  think  that  you  state  the  matter  quite  right  in 
regard  to  the  mixture  of  fluids  if  they  were  continuous. 
The  mixing  of  water  as  I  regard  it  would  be  like  this,  if 
it  were  continuous  and  not  molecular.  Suppose  you  should 
take  strips  of  white  and  red  glass  and  heat  them  until  soft 
and  twist  them  together.  Keep  on  drawing  them  out  and 
doubling  them  up  and  twisting  them  together.  It  would 
soon  require  a  microscope  to  distinguish  the  red  and  white 
glass,  which  would  be  drawn  out  into  thinner  and  thinner 
filaments  if  the  matter  were  continuous.  But  it  would  be 
always  only  a  matter  of  optical  power  to  distinguish  per- 
fectly the  portions  of  red  and  white  glass.  The  stirring  up 
of  water  from  two  pails  would  not  really  mix  them  but 
only  entangle  filaments  from  the  pails. 

"To  come  to  the  case  of  energy.  All  our  ideas  concern- 
ing energy  seem  to  require  that  it  is  capable  of  gradual  in- 
crease. Thus  the  energy  due  to  velocity  can  increase  con- 
tinuously if  velocity  can.  Since  the  energy  is  as  the  square 
of  the  velocity,  if  the  velocity  can  only  increase  discontinu- 
ously  by  equal  increments,  the  energy  of  a  body  will  in- 
crease by  unequal  increments  in  such  a  way  as  to  make 
the  exchange  of  energy  between  bodies  a  very  awkward 
matter  to  adjust. 

"But  apart  from  the  question  of  the  increase  of  energy 


586  THE  MONIST. 

by  discontinuous  increments,  the  question  of  relative  and 
absolute  motion  makes  it  very  hard  to  give  a  particular 
position  to  energy.  Since  the  'energy'  we  speak  of  in  any 
case  is  not  one  quantity  but  may  be  interpreted  in  a  great 
many  ways.  Take  the  important  case  of  two  equal  elastic 
balls.  One,  moving,  strikes  the  other  at  rest,  we  say,  and 
gives  it  nearly  all  its  energy.  But  we  have  no  right  to 
call  one  ball  at  rest  and  we  can  not  say  (as  anything  ab- 
solute) which  of  the  balls  has  lost  and  which  has  gained 
energy.  If  there  is  such  a  thing  as  absolute  energy  of 
motion  it  is  something  entirely  unknowable  by  us.  Take 
the  solar  system,  supposed  isolated.  We  may  take  as  our 
origin  of  coordinates  the  center  of  gravity  of  the  system. 
Or  we  may  take  an  origin  with  respect  to  which  the  center 
of  gravity  of  the  solar  system  has  any  (constant)  velocity. 
The  kinetic  energy  of  the  earth,  for  example,  may  have 
any  value  whatever,  and  the  principle  of  the  conservation 
of  energy  will  hold  in  any  case  for  the  whole  solar  system. 
But  the  shifting  of  energy  from  one  planet  to  another  will 
take  place  entirely  differently  when  we  estimate  the  ener- 
gies with  reference  to  different  origins. 

"It  does  not  seem  to  me  that  your  ideas  fit  in  with  what 
we  know  about  nature.  If  you  ask  my  advice,  I  should  not 
advise  you  to  try  to  publish  them. 

"At  best  you  would  be  entering  into  a  discussion  (per- 
haps not  in  bad  company)  in  which  words  would  play  a 
greater  part  than  precise  ideas. 

"This  is  the  way  I  feel  about  it. 
"I  remain 

"Yours  faithfully, 

J.  W.  GIBBS." 

Professor  Gibbs's  criticism  of  the  illustration  of  water- 
mixture  is  evidently  just.  Another  might  well  have  been 
used  where  the  things  mixed  are  not  material — for  instance 


ATOMIC  THEORIES  OF  ENERGY.  587 

the  value  of  money  deposited  in  a  bank.  If  A  and  B  each 
deposits  $100  to  Cs  credit  and  C  then  draws  $10,  there  is 
evidently  no  way  of  determining  what  part  of  it  came  from 
A  and  what  from  B.  The  structure  of  "value,"  in  other 
words,  is  perfectly  continuous.  Professor  Gibbs's  objections 
to  an  "atomic"  theory  of  the  structure  of  energy  are  most 
interesting.  The  difficulties  that  it  involves  are  not  over- 
stated. In  1897  they  made  it  unnecessary,  but  since  that 
time  considerations  have  been  brought  forward,  and  gen- 
erally recognized,  which  may  make  it  necessary  to  brave 
those  difficulties. 

Planck's  theory  was  suggested  by  the  apparent  neces- 
sity of  modifying  the  generally  accepted  theory  of  statis- 
tical equilibrium  involving  the  so-called  "law  of  equipar- 
tition,"  enunciated  first  for  gases  and  extended  to  liquids 
and  solids. 

In  the  first  place  the  kinetic  theory  fixes  the  number  of 
degrees  of  freedom  of  each  gaseous  molecule,  which  would 
be  three  for  argon,  for  instance,  and  five  for  oxygen.  But 
what  prevents  either  from  having  the  six  degrees  to  which 
ordinary  mechanical  theory  entitles  it  ?  Furthermore,  the 
oxygen  spectrum  has  more  than  five  lines,  and  the  molecule 
must  therefore  vibrate  in  more  than  five  modes.  "Why," 
asks  Poincare,  "do  certain  degrees  of  freedom  appear  to 
play  no  part  here ;  why  are  they,  so  to  speak,  'ankylosed'  ?" 
Again,  suppose  a  system  in  statistical  equilibrium,  each 
part  gaining  on  an  average,  in  a  short  time,  exactly  as 
much  as  it  loses.  If  the  system  consists  of  molecules  and 
ether,  as  the  former  have  a  finite  number  of  degrees  of  free- 
dom and  the  latter  an  infinite  number,  the  unmodified  law 
of  equipartition  would  require  that  the  ether  should  finally 
appropriate  all  energy,  leaving  none  of  it  to  the  matter. 
To  escape  this  conclusion  we  have  Rayleigh's  law  that  the 
radiated  energy,  for  a  given  wavelength,  is  proportional 
to  the  absolute  temperature,  and  for  a  given  temperature 


588  THE  MONIST. 

is  in  inverse  ratio  to  the  fourth  power  of  the  wave-length. 
This  is  found  by  Planck  to  be  experimentally  unverifiable, 
the  radiation  being  less  for  small  wave-lengths  and  low 
temperatures,  than  the  law  requires. 

Still  again,  the  specific  heats  of  solids,  instead  of  being 
sensibly  constant  at  all  temperatures,  are  found  to  diminish 
rapidly  in  the  low  temperatures  now  available  in  liquid 
air  or  hydrogen  and  apparently  tend  to  disappear  at  ab- 
solute zero.  "All  takes  place/7  says  Poincare,  "as  if  these 
molecules  lost  some  of  their  degrees  of  freedom  in  cooling 
— as  if  some  of  their  articulations  froze  at  the  limit." 

Plank  attempts  to  explain  these  facts  by  introducing 
the  idea  of  what  he  calls  "quanta"  of  energy.  To  quote 
from  Poincare's  paper: 

"How  should  we  picture  a  radiating  body?  We  know 
that  a  Hertz  resonator  sends  into  the  ether  Hertzian  waves 
that  are  identical  with  luminous  waves:  an  incandescent 
body  must  then  be  regarded  as  containing  a  very  great 
number  of  tiny  resonators.  When  the  body  is  heated, 
these  resonators  acquire  energy,  start  vibrating  and  con- 
sequently radiate. 

"Planck's  hypothesis  consists  in  the  supposition  that 
each  of  these  resonators  can  acquire  or  lose  energy  only 
by  abrupt  jumps,  in  such  a  way  that  the  store  of  energy 
that  it  possesses  must  always  be  a  multiple  of  a  constant 
quantity,  which  he  calls  a  'quantum' — must  be  composed  of 
a  whole  number  of  quanta.  This  indivisible  unit,  this 
quantum,  is  not  the  same  for  all  resonators ;  it  is  in  inverse 
ratio  to  the  wave-length,  so  that  resonators  of  short  period 
can  take  in  energy  only  in  large  pieces,  while  those  of  long 
period  can  absorb  or  give  it  out  by  small  bits.  What  is  the 
result  ?  Great  effort  is  necessary  to  agitate  a  short-period 
resonator,  since  this  requires  at  least  a  quantity  of  energy 
equal  to  its  quantum,  which  is  great.  The  chances  are, 
then,  that  these  resonators  will  keep  quiet,  especially  if  the 


ATOMIC  THEORIES  OF  ENERGY.  589 

temperature  is  low,  and  it  is  for  this  reason  that  there  is 
relatively  little  short-wave  radiation  in  'black  radiation/. . . 
The  diminution  of  specific-heats  is  explained  similarly: 
When  the  temperature  falls,  a  large  number  of  vibrators 
fall  below  their  quantum  and  cease  to  vibrate,  so  that  the 
total  energy  diminishes  faster  than  the  old  theories  re- 
quire." 

Here  we  have  the  germs  of  an  atomic  theory  of  energy. 
As  Poincare  now  points  out,  the  trouble  is  that  the  quanta 
are  not  constant.  In  his  study  of  the  matter  he  notes  that 
the  work  of  Prof.  Wilhelm  Wien,  of  Wurzburg,  leads  by 
theory  to  precisely  the  conclusion  announced  by  Planck 
that  if  we  are  to  hold  to  the  accepted  ideas  of  statistical 
equilibrium  the  energy  can  vary  only  by  quanta  inversely 
proportional  to  wave-length.  The  mechanical  property 
of  the  resonators  imagined  by  Planck  is  therefore  precisely 
that  which  Wien's  theory  requires.  If  we  are  to  suppose 
atoms  of  energy,  therefore,  they  must  be  variable  atoms. 
There  are  other  objections  which  need  not  be  touched  upon 
here,  the  whole  theory  being  in  a  very  early  stage.  To 
quote  Poincare  again: 

"The  new  conception  is  seductive  from  a  certain  stand- 
point: for  some  time  the  tendency  has  been  toward  atom- 
ism. Matter  appears  to  us  as  formed  of  indivisible  atoms ; 
electricity  is  no  longer  continuous,  not  infinitely  divisible, 
it  resolves  itself  into  equally-charged  electrons;  we  have 
also  now  the  magneton,  or  atom  of  magnetism.  From  this 
point  of  view  the  quanta  appear  as  atoms  of  energy.  Un- 
fortunately the  comparison  may  not  be  pushed  to  the  limit ; 
a  hydrogen  atom  is  really  invariable ....  The  electrons  pre- 
serve their  individuality  amid  the  most  divers  vicissitudes, 
is  it  the  same  with  the  atoms  of  energy?  We  have,  for 
instance,  three  quanta  of  energy  in  a  resonator  whose 
wave-length  is  3 ;  this  passes  to  a  second  resonator  whose 
wave-length  is  5 ;  it  now  represents  not  3  but  5  quanta, 


590 


THE  MONIST. 


since  the  quantum  of  the  new  resonator  is  smaller  and  in 
the  transformation  the  number  of  atoms  and  the  size  of 
each  has  changed." 

If,  however,  we  replace  the  atom  of  energy  by  an 
"atom  of  action,"  these  atoms  may  be  considered  equal 
and  invariable.  The  whole  study  of  thermodynamic  equi- 
librium has  been  reduced  by  the  French  mathematical 
school  to  a  question  of  probability.  "The  probability  of  a 
continuous  variable  is  obtained  by  considering  elementary 
independent  domains  of  equal  probability ....  In  the  classic 
dynamics  we  use,  to  find  these  elementary  domains,  the 
theorem  that  two  physical  states  of  which  one  is  the  neces- 
sary effect  of  the  other  are  equally  probable.  In  a  physical 
system  if  we  represent  by  q  one  of  the  generalized  coordi- 
nates and  by  p  the  corresponding  momentum,  according 
to  Liouville's  theorem  the  domain  f  fdpdq,  considered  at  a 
given  instant,  is  invariable  with  respect  to  the  time  if  p  and 
q  vary  according  to  Hamilton's  equations.  On  the  other 
hand  p  and  q  may,  at  a  given  instant  take  all  possible  val- 
ues, independent  of  each  other.  Whence  it  follows  that  the 
elementary  domain  is  infinitely  small,  of  the  magnitude 
dpdq.  . .  .  The  new  hypothesis  has  for  its  object  to  restrict 
the  variability  of  p  and  q  so  that  these  variables  will  only 
change  by  jumps ....  Thus  the  number  of  elementary  do- 
mains of  probability  is  reduced  and  the  extent  of  each  is 
augmented.  The  hypothesis  of  quanta  of  action  consists 
in  supposing  that  these  domains  are  all  equal  and  no  longer 
infinitely  small  but  finite  and  that  for  each  ffdpdq=h, 
h  being  a  constant." 

Put  a  little  less  mathematically,  this  simply  means  that 
as  energy  equals  action  multiplied  by  frequency,  the  fact 
that  the  quantum  of  energy  is  proportional  to  the  frequency 
(or  inversely  to  the  wave-length  as  stated  above)  is  due 
simply  to  the  fact  that  the  quantum  of  action  is  constant— 
a  real  atom.  The  general  effect  on  our  physical  concep- 


ATOMIC  THEORIES  OF  ENERGY. 

tions,  however,  is  the  same:  we  have  a  purely  discontin- 
uous universe — discontinuous  not  only  in  matter  but  in 
energy  and  the  flow  of  time.  M.  Poincare  thus  puts  it : 

"A  physical  system  is  susceptible  only  of  a  finite  num- 
ber of  distinct  states;  it  leaps  from  one  of  these  to  the 
next  without  passing  through  any  continuous  series  of 
intermediate  states." 

He  notes  later : 

"The  universe,  then,  leaps  suddenly  from  one  state  to 
another ;  but  in  the  interval  it  must  remain  immovable,  and 
the  divers  instants  during  which  it  keeps  in  the  same  state 
can  no  longer  be  discriminated  from  one  another ;  we  thus 
reach  a  conception  of  the  discontinuous  variation  of  time 
— the  atom  of  time." 

I  quote  in  conclusion,  Poincare's  final  remarks: 

"The  present  state  of  the  question  is  thus  as  follows: 
the  old  theories,  which  hitherto  seemed  to  account  for  all 
the  known  phenomena,  have  met  with  an  unexpected  ob- 
stacle. Seemingly  a  modification  becomes  necessary.  A 
hypothesis  has  presented  itself  to  M.  Planck's  mind,  but 
so  strange  a  one  that  one  is  tempted  to  seek  every  means  of 
escaping  it ;  these  means,  however,  have  been  sought  vainly. 
The  new  theory,  however,  raises  a  host  of  difficulties,  many 
of  which  are  real  and  not  simply  illusions  due  to  the  indo- 
lence of  our  minds,  unwilling  to  change  their  modes  of 
thought 

"Is  discontinuity  to  reign  throughout  the  physical  uni- 
verse, and  is  its  triumph  definitive?  Or  rather  shall  we 
find  that  it  is  but  apparent  and  hides  a  series  of  continuous 
processes  ? ....  To  try  to  give  an  opinion  just  now  on  these 
questions  would  only  be  to  waste  ink." 

It  only  remains  to  call  attention  again  to  the  fact  that 
this  conception  of  the  discontinuity  of  energy,  the  accept- 
ance of  which  Poincare  says  would  be  "the  most  profound 
revolution  that  natural  philosophy  has  undergone  since 


592  THE  MONIST. 

Newton"  was  suggested  by  the  present  writer  fifteen  years 
ago.  Its  reception  and  serious  consideration  by  one  of 
the  first  mathematical  physicists  of  the  world  seems  a  suf- 
ficient justification  of  its  suggestion  then  as  a  legitimate 
scientific  hypothesis. 

ARTHUR  E.  BOSTWICK. 
ST.  Louis,  Mo. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

HENRI  BERGSON,  PRAGMATISM  AND  SCHOPENHAUER. 

The  history  of  philosophy  is  like  one  of  the  ancestral  galleries 
in  ancient  European  castles.  At  first  glance  you  find  yourself  before 
a  bewildering  variety  of  individuals,  but  if  you  look  closer  you  dis- 
cover that  certain  family  traits  reappear  again  and  again.  In  the 
history  of  philosophy  a  similar  variety  of  individual  systems  at  first 
confuses  the  student.  But  upon  closer  scrutiny  he  will  find  that 
here  too  the  bewilderment  ceases,  that  certain  outlines  are  typical 
for  the  structure  of  a  great  number  of  systems  and  that  almost 
every  individual  system  belongs  to  such  a  type  of  structure.  Con- 
sidered in  this  light  the  history  of  philosophy  presents  a  few  types 
of  thought  which  undergo  slight  changes  and  show  a  slow  develop- 
ment according  to  the  intellectual  conditions  of  the  century  in  which 
the  philosopher  moulded  his  system. 

The  systematic  structure  to  be  considered  in  this  paper  is  a 
very  modern  one,  namely  Henri  Bergson's  philosophy.  From  a 
purely  philosophical  standpoint  it  was  severely  criticized  in  the  last 
number  of  this  magazine.1  In  this  number  it  may  be  scrutinized 
from  a  purely  historical  standpoint. 

Among  laymen  Bergson's  name  carries  with  it  a  certain  feeling 
of  mystic  refinement.  However  little  they  may  know  about  him, 
they  instinctively  expect  such  an  appeal  to  their  artistic  natures  as 
they  would  from  a  sculpture  by  Auguste  Rodin  or  a  drama  by 
Maeterlinck.  They  instinctively  feel  the  kind  of  a  man  who  is  about 
to  confront  them  and  their  feeling  is  probably  correct. 

Feeling,  however,  is  quite  a  different  thing  from  knowing. 
Strange  to  say,  philosophers  are  greatly  at  variance  as  to  the  place 
of  Bergson's  philosophy  in  the  gallery  of  philosophical  systems. 

1  See  "The  Philosophy  of  Bergson"  by  Mr.  Bertram!  Russell,  Monist,  July, 
1912.  Cf.  also  in  the  same  number,  "Bergson  and  Religion"  by  Dr.  James  G. 
Townsend,  and  "Kant  and  Bergson"  by  Dr.  Bruno  Jordan. 


594  THE  MONIST. 

Here  is  the  struggle  of  a  man's  mind,  some  philosophers  say,  which 
can  be  compared  in  importance  only  with  the  philosophy  of  Kant, 
while  still  very  different.  Others  are  reminded  of  Hegel  and  others 
of  Berkeley;  while  American  pragmatists  say  that  Bergson  is  a 
pragmatist.  Others  again  are  of  the  opinion  that  it  is  quite  out 
of  the  question  to  compare  Bergson  at  all  with  philosophers  of  any 
other  school.  They  say  he  is  unique;  he  is  no  type,  but  has  an 
individuality  of  his  own. 

We  shall  see.  It  is  certain  however  that  it  would  be  rather 
strange  if  Bergson  were  not  a  type,  notwithstanding  his  marked 
individuality ;  if  his  philosophy  really  bore  no  relation  to  philosophies 
of  former  days.  This  would  mean  that  in  the  development  of 
philosophical  traditions  a  structure  of  philosophy  had  arisen  no 
likeness  to  which  had  ever  been  seen  before,  that  a  child  without 
ancestors  had  been  brought  to  light;  but  this  is  not  very  probable. 
To  inquire  therefore  after  the  historical  antecedents  of  Bergson's 
philosophy  would  mean  to  ask  whether  its  structure  is  entirely  new 
or  only  a  transformation  of  what  already  existed,  and  in  the  latter 
case  the  questions  arise,  who  used  this  structure  before  Bergson? 
Who  among  the  philosophers  of  former  days  may  be  called  nearest 
akin  to  him?  Which  philosophical  tradition  is  continued  by  Berg- 
son's  thought?  These  are  the  questions  which  I  shall  try  to  answer 

in  this  paper. 

*       *       * 

Which  philosophical  tradition  is  continued  by  Bergson?  "The 
pragmatistic  one,"  say  the  American  pragmatists ;  "Bergson  is  a 
pragmatist."  I  do  not  hesitate  to  agree  that  Bergson  really  is  a 
pragmatist,  and  here  are  the  proofs. 

Pragmatism  holds  that  what  we  call  reality,  world,  object  of 
knowledge,  is  not  something  independent  of  us,  but  rather  a  man-made 
picture,  a  raw  material  transformed  into  a  complicated  instrument 
for  action.  "The  world  is  only  an  opportunity  to  do  our  duty," 
Fichte  was  wont  to  say.  "The  world  is  only  an  expedient  for  our 
action,"  the  pragmatists  of  to-day  tell  us.  Seeing,  hearing,  smelling, 
touching  the  world,  as  well  as  considering  it  as  a  multitude  of 
atoms,  electrons,  ions,  means  nothing  else  than  a  preparation  to 
grapple  with  the  world. 

This  doctrine  becomes  very  evident  in  Bergson's  philosophy. 
For  Henri  Bergson  the  essence  of  man  is  life.  What  we  call  man 
is  not  so  much  the  human  body  nor  a  soul-substance  within  that 
body,  but  rather  a  dramatic  performance,  a  continual  course  of 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  595 

events,  of  visions,  sounds,  feelings,  images,  thoughts  and  especially 
of  actions.  Man  means  an  elan  vital,  a  life-current  running  along 
seventy,  eighty  or  ninety  years. 

If  this  is  so,  what  is  the  business  of  that  life-current?  To 
what  purpose  is  that  action  acting?  In  agreement  with  the  biol- 
ogists Bergson  would  answer  that  the  business  of  life  is  to  find 
its  way  among  other  life-currents.  But  if  we  look  closer  we  shall 
see  that  these  other  life-currents  differ  widely  from  one  another, 
that  man  treats  them  at  least  in  very  different  ways,  some  of  them 
as  matter  only  and  others  as  matter  but  also  as  souls. 

For  the  present  we  shall  disregard  life-currents  treated  as 
souls.  As  far  as  their  treatment  as  pure  matter  is  concerned, 
Bergson  is  among  the  pragmatists.  Man  is  different  from  most 
animals  in  that  he  has  hands  and  uses  them  not  only  for  climbing 
trees  as  the  monkeys  do  but  for  providing  instruments.  It  would 
not  be  too  bold  to  say  that  man  has  made  his  hands  longer  and 
stronger  by  utilizing  matter  for  instruments.  The  axe,  the  arrow, 
the  target  are  such  artificial  hands,  not  to  mention  the  enormous  de- 
velopment of  inventions  during  the  last  centuries,  all  tending  to 
the  same  end. 

This  leads  to  the  question  of  how  this  mechanical  point  of  view 
influences  our  knowledge  of  reality.  The  answer  is  very  simple. 
Since  man  intends  to  use  reality  for  instrumental  purposes  it  appears 
to  him  entirely  as  an  object  of  action — either  to  act  upon  or  to  act 
with. 

We  seldom  realize  how  much  difference  such  a  point  of  view 
makes  in  our  knowledge.  A  desk  in  my  study  may  serve  as  a 
simple  instance.  Everybody  agrees  that  it  is  a  desk.  But  "desk" 
means  an  instrument  either  to  put  a  manuscript  on,  to  read  a  book 
on,  to  fit  a  lamp  on,  etc.  In  other  words,  from  the  very  beginning 
we  all  acknowledge  a  certain  piece  of  wood  as  a  practical  object 
destined  for  practical  purposes,  and  it  would  be  surprisingly  hard 
for  us  to  free  ourselves  from  this  impression,  to  look  at  that  object 
and  not  identify  it  with  a  desk.  But  desk  means  instrument  and  in- 
strument means  possibility  of  action.  I  shall  return  to  this  point 
very  soon. 

Meanwhile  another  reflection  may  serve  to  clear  up  this  situa- 
tion still  further.  I  say  that  to  all  of  us  the  desk  appears  as  a  desk. 
We  cannot  help  it.  Still  the  impression  of  the  desk  is  by  no  means 
the  same  to  all  of  us,  for  in  addition  to  its  being  acknowledged  as  a 
desk  it  may  be  recognized  in  many  other  ways.  Let  me  suppose 


596  THE  MONIST. 

that  a  dealer  in  woods  happens  to  examine  my  desk.  He  will  see 
many  features  in  it  which  other  people  do  not  observe.  He  will  not 
only  infer  but  actually  see  the  quality  of  the  wood  and  probably  tell 
its  cash-value  off-hand;  while  all  that  other  people  see  is  that  it  is 
"apparently  of  oak"  and  possibly  that  it  looks  "rather  nice."  The 
merchant  being  a  connoisseur  actually  sees  more  than  other  people. 
Now  perhaps  a  carpenter  looks  at  the  desk,  then  an  artist,  then  a 
botanist,  then  a  chemist,  then  a  physicist.  The  layman  would 
simply  laugh  when  the  botanist  says  that  the  desk  is  a  conglomera- 
tion of  cells,  or  the  physicist  that  it  is  a  heap  of  molecules,  or  the 
chemist  that  it  is  a  multitude  of  atoms.  Still  these  are  the  ways 
in  which  the  desk  would  be  regarded  by  these  men.  It  is  only  the 
point  of  view  which  is  different. 

In  other  respects  however  we  all  are  taking  the  same  point  of 
view,  for  to  all  of  us,  whether  layman,  merchant  or  physicist,  the 
desk  appears  as  a  desk,  and  if  it  does  not  appear  as  a  desk,  it  would 
at  least  appear  as  a  table.  And  if  it  does  not  appear  as  a  table  it 
would  at  least  appear  as  a  "thing,"  and  "thing"  always  means,  if  we 
believe  Bergson,  something  to  act  upon  or  to  act  with. 

It  is  only  the  point  of  view  which  is  different.  In  other  respects 
however  all  are  taking  the  same  point  of  view,  for  to  all  of  us, 
whether  layman,  merchant  or  physicist,  the  desk  appears  as  a  desk, 
or  if  not  as  a  desk,  at  least  as  a  table.  And  if  it  does  not  appear 
as  a  table  it  would  at  least  appear  as  a  "thing,"  and  "thing"  always 
means,  if  we  believe  Bergson,  something  to  act  upon  or  to  act  with. 

Hence,  in  considering  the  world  as  an  accumulation  of  things 
we  have  already  taken  a  certain  limited  point  of  view;  we  are  on 
the  way  to  treat  the  universe  as  an  object  and  eventually  as  a  means 
of  action.  We  have  taken  the  decisive  step,  and  cannot  now  go 
back.  We  have  made  the  start  in  our  calculation  and  it  will  proceed 

accordingly. 

*       *       * 

It  is  interesting  that  Bergson  considers  three-dimensional  space 
as  one  of  the  most  important  elements  in  the  method  by  which  the 
world  is  conceived  as  a  means  for  action.  To  see  things  in  space 
means  to  consider  them  as  objects  to  act  upon.  Space  is  a  kind  of 
uniform  which  we  put  upon  the  world  in  order  to  control  it,  for  to 
control  things  we  cannot  care  what  they  are  in  themselves ;  we  must 
care  what  they  may  be  to  us.  Hence  we  deprive  them  of  their  very 
essence;  we  treat  them  by  a  scheme,  which  enables  us  to  divide 
things  up  quite  at  will — while  according  to  Bergson  things  in  them- 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  597 

selves  are  indivisible,  although,  as  he  expresses  it,  they  have  a  cer- 
tain "ballast"  of  that  scheme. 

Our  three-dimensional  space  is  a  scheme  for  division  and  noth- 
ing else;  its  very  homogeneity  is  the  means  by  which  we  divide 
things.  This  is  most  apparent  in  theoretical  physics  where  all 
plurality  of  our  pluralistic  world  is  eliminated  and  only  shadowy 
colorless  sections  of  space  remain  where  before  we  saw  blue  and  red 
and  green  and  yellow,  where  we  heard  noise  and  music,  smelled 
odors  and  tasted  sweet  and  bitter.  Theoretical  physics  is  space 
triumphant,  which  means  it  is  a  triumph  of  practical  handling  of  the 
world.  Plurality  once  eliminated  from  the  world  there  is  no  limit 
for  divisions.  We  may  divide  indefinitely,  and  dividing  will  doubt- 
less contribute  much  toward  our  practical  control  over  the  world. 

*       *       * 

It  is  a  very  significant  fact  that  we  treat  time  in  a  similar  way 
again  and  again;  we  spatialize  it.  If  somebody  knocks  at  the  door 
three  times  in  succession  and  we  try  to  recall  that  succession  of 
knocks,  we  discover  in  ourselves  a  certain  inability  to  do  so.  Instead 
of  representing  the  three  knocks  as  a  real  sequence  in  time  we  find 
ourselves  fancying  them  one  beside  or  behind  the  other,  quite  as 
though  they  were  three  pearls  on  a  cord  or  three  blots  on  a  line. 
We  are  almost  compelled  to  do  so;  for  to  recall  something  means 
to  see  it  all  at  once,  and  to  see  all  at  once  is  precisely  not  to  see 
one  part  after  the  other  in  succession,  but  to  perceive  them  simul- 
taneously. Hence  we  spatialize  time,  and  in  so  doing  we  are  tend- 
ing again  towards  its  homogeneity.  Of  course  we  are  not  treating 
time  as  three-dimensional  space — that  would  not  do;  but  modern 
scientists  treat  it  as  a  "fourth  dimension"  of  space,  and  common 
sense  regards  it  as  a  one-dimensional  line.  The  next  step  in  this 
procedure  will  be  to  eliminate  all  plurality  of  concrete  experience 
from  that  line,  to  divide  up  time  quite  as  arbitrarily  as  space  and 
to  deal  with  time  too,  regardless  of  its  contents,  as  suits  our  purpose. 
The  dial  on  a  watch  is  nothing  but  a  graphic  demonstration  of  such 
a  one-dimensional  time-line,  its  straightness  being  turned  into  a 
circle. 

Bergson's  idea  of  the  business  of  understanding  is  now  suffi- 
ciently clear.  Understanding  is  an  instrument  by  which  human  life 
works  its  way  through  its  surroundings.  Moreover  it  is  an  instru- 
ment by  which  human  life  continually  makes  use  of  homogeneous 
schemes,  treating  simultaneous  impressions  by  space  and  successive 
impressions  by  spatialized  time.  This  threefoldness  of  understanding 


598  THE  MONIST. 

— practical  use,  homogeneous  space  and  spatialized  time — may  still 
become  important  for  our  later  discussion.  For  the  present  it  suf- 
fices to  state  that  understanding  is  to  Bergson  an  instrument  for 
practical  use.  This  is  the  reason  why  in  America  he  is  called  a 

pragmatist. 

*  *      * 

And  now  in  seeming  contradiction  to  my  own  words,  and  in 
open  contradiction  to  the  theory  of  most  American  philosophers,  I 
say  that  Bergson  is  not  a  pragmatist.  He  is  the  very  foe  of  the 
pragmatists ;  for  to  tell  the  truth,  what  pragmatism  advocates,  Berg- 
sonian  philosophy  opposes.  It  is  one  of  the  main  features  of  this 
philosophy  to  disregard  the  whole  realm  of  understanding  as  a  realm 
for  practical  use.  To  Bergson's  mind  it  is  precisely  the  pragmatic 
attitude  that  hinders  understanding  from  entering  philosophy — and 
Bergson  is  after  all  a  philosopher.  He  leaves  to  pragmatism  the 
realm  of  science  and  common  sense,  but  in  philosophy  he  protests 
against  it. 

To  Bergson's  mind  philosophy  begins  where  pragmatism  ceases. 
To  be  a  Bergsonian  philosopher  I  must  rid  myself  of  pragmatistic 
habits.  It  is  pragmatistic  to  look  at  everything  from  the  point  of 
view  of  action,  hence  it  is  philosophic  to  discard  that  point  of  view. 
It  is  pragmatistic  to  consider  the  world  as  wrapped  in  space,  hence 
it  is  philosophic  to  free  the  world  from  space.  It  is  pragmatistic 
to  spatialize  time,  hence  it  is  philosophic  to  remove  that  spatiali- 
zation. 

A  -Bergsonian  philosopher  is  a  thinker  freed  from  all  prag- 
matism. He  no  longer  looks  for  the  practical  use  of  things,  but 
looks  to  things  for  their  own  sake.  His  mind  no  longer  works  to 
make  headway  for  life,  but  it  turns  itself  round  and  looks  at  life 
itself  as  it  goes  on  within  him.  Bergsonian  philosophy  is  conscious- 
ness of  life  itself  freed  from  its  practical  service. 

*  *       * 

And  now  our  thoughts  do  not  leave  Bergson  in  passing  over 
to  Schopenhauer  and  attempting  to  throw  light  on  Bergson's  ideas 
by  the  philosophy  of  Schopenhauer  and  on  Schopenhauer's  ideas 
by  the  philosophy  of  Bergson. 

Like  Bergson,  Schopenhauer  is  a  pragmatist;  like  the  prag- 
matism of  Bergson,  that  of  Schopenhauer  holds  good  for  understand- 
ing only;  and  as  for  Bergson,  so  for  Schopenhauer,  philosophy  be- 
gins just  where  understanding  and  pragmatism  cease.2 

aCf.  Schopenhauer,  Werke  (ed.  Grisebach),  I,  p.  242. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  599 

Thus  understanding  plays  quite  a  similar  role  with  Schopen- 
hauer as  with  Bergson.  It  is  very  significant  that  Bergson  and 
Schopenhauer  use  the  same  simile.  Both  call  understanding  "a 
lantern"  which  life  has  kindled  in  order  to  find  its  way  through  the 
world.  For  both  this  "lantern,"  originally  used  for  a  limited  ser- 
vice, has  extended  its  light  more  and  more  until  now  it  shines  over 
the  whole  universe,  or  at  least  what  it  calls  a  "universe." 

Now  the  "universe"  over  which  this  lantern  sheds  its  light 
is  matter.  Our  earth  and  all  that  lives  on  earth  is  matter.  The 
moon,  the  sun,  the  planets,  all  solar  systems  are  matter.  But  for 
Bergson  as  for  Schopenhauer  "matter"  is  nothing  but  reality  treated 
by  the  methods  of  understanding,  covered  with  three-dimensional 
space,  put  into  spatialized  time  and  considered  pragmatically  for 
the  single  purpose  of  action. 

For  Bergson  matter  is  simply  correlative  to  understanding;  it 
is  the  only  means  by  which  understanding  knows  reality.  Schopen- 
hauer takes  exactly  the  same  position.  "Matter,"  he  writes,  "and 
hence  the  appearance  of  the  whole  universe,  is  there  for  under- 
standing only.  Understanding  is  its  support,  the  condition  of  its 
very  existence;  it  is  its  necessary  correlatum."3 

It  is  important  to  realize  that  this  coincidence  between  Bergson 
and  Schopenhauer  is  not  insignificant,  but  indicates  a  very  interesting 
and  far-reaching  identity  in  the  main  structure  of  their  systems. 
That  understanding  is  limited  to  matter  and  matter  limited  to  under- 
standing is  of  decisive  consequence  for  the  whole  development  of 
both  philosophies. 

*       *       * 

But  the  coincidence  between  Bergson's  and  Schopenhauer's 
idea  of  understanding  goes  much  farther  than  this;  for  precisely 
the  same  three  functions  of  understanding  with  regard  to  matter 
pointed  out  by  Bergson  are  likewise  pointed  out  by  Schopenhauer. 
If  Bergson  declares  that  the  only  aim  of  understanding  is  to  have 
the  possibility  of  acting  upon  its  environment,  and  that  this  is  the 
reason  why  it  materialises  everything,  Schopenhauer  would  say 
that  causality  is  the  only  category  of  understanding,  for  under- 
standing is  there  solely  to  act  upon  its  environment.  That  is  the 
service  forced  upon  understanding  by  the  all-powerful  will  to  live, 
and  that  too  is  the  main  reason  why  understanding  transforms 
everything  into  matter.  In  other  words,  Bergson's  pragmatism  of 
understanding  and  Schopenhauer's  doctrine  of  causality  as  the  only 

8  Werke,  II,  p.  160. 


600  THE  MONIST. 

function  of  understanding  tend  precisely  towards  the  same  point, 
a  point  of  greatest  consequence,  in  fact  a  cornerstone  in  the  structure 
of  both  systems. 

For  Schopenhauer  as  for  Bergson  understanding  stands  for  ac- 
tivity and  for  activity  only.  Its  functions  to  provide  for  space  and 
time,  are  subordinate  to  that  main  function.  They  are  the  means 
by  which  understanding  succeeds  in  materializing  the  world  for  the 
purpose  of  action. 

When  Bergson  says  that  in  order  to  handle  the  world  for  action 
understanding  covers  it  with  three-dimensional  homogeneous  space, 
Schopenhauer  would  say  that  three-dimensional  homogeneous  space 
is  one  of  the  two  indispensable  intuitions  a  priori  of  understanding. 
That  space  is  a  priori  for  Schopenhauer  and  possibly  a  posteriori  for 
Bergson  is  of  no  consequence  for  this  part  of  our  comparison.  But 
it  certainly  is  of  very  great  consequence  that  in  the  philosophy  of  both 
understanding  uses  space  as  its  most  important  instrument  in  mate- 
rializing the  world  for  the  purpose  of  action. 

The  other  instrument  by  which  understanding  materializes  the 
world  is  time.  Bergson  says  that  for  this  purpose  time  is  spatialized. 
Schopenhauer  declares  that  time  is  the  other  of  the  two  "intuitions 
a  priori"  of  understanding.  Now  there  is  apparently  no  similarity 
at  all  between  the  ideas  of  Schopenhauer  and  Bergson;  and  still, 
on  looking  closer,  a  careful  observer  will  discover  that  there  is  a 
similarity,  and  indeed  a  far  greater  one  than  would  be  suspected. 
I  venture  to  call  special  attention  to  this  point. 

What  distinctive  feature  of  space  makes  it  appear  to  Bergson 
particularly  adapted  for  the  practical  purpose  of  understanding? 
Certainly  not  that  space  is  three-dimensional,  but  that  three-dimen- 
sional space  is  homogeneous.  Space  is  fit  for  action  solely  because 
of  its  homogeneity.  With  homogeneity  arbitrary  divisibility  is  pos- 
sible, and  with  arbitrary  divisibility  understanding  finds  its  way 
to  handle  reality  instrumentally — that  is  all. 

Let  us  pass  to  time.  What  distinctive  feature  of  time  makes 
it  appear  to  Bergson  as  being  particularly  adapted  for  the  practical 
purposes  of  understanding?  Bergson  finds  this  distinctive  feature 
in  the  fact  that  we  "spatialize"  time.  But  what  does  he  mean  by 
spatializing  time?  Again  nothing  but  an  attempt  to  treat  time 
like  space,  namely  as  a  homogeneous  something.  It  is  not  the  one 
dimension  nor  the  straightness  of  the  line,  that  "spatializes"  time; 
but  its  uniformity,  its  homogeneity,  its  divisibility  at  any  point,  and 
hence  its  possibility  to  be  handled  instrumentally.  Homogeneity, 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  6OI 

divisibility  at  any  point,  is  the  only  quality  for  which  understanding 
cares.  It  is  wholly  indifferent  to  everything  else  in  space  and  in 
spatialized  time. 

Passing  to  Schopenhauer  we  discover  that  the  reason  why  he, 
like  his  master  Kant,  considers  space  and  time  as  "intuitions  a 
priori"  is  again  their  all-embracing  homogeneity.  The  reader  re- 
members Kant's  demonstration  of  this  in  his  Critique  of  Pure  Rea- 
son. Space  and  time  have  the  peculiarity  of  not  being  "concepts," 
but  "intuitions,"  because  they  are  spread  out  with  absolute  uniform- 
ity, with  absolute  homogeneity,  which  does  not  allow  the  distinction 
between  different  (three-dimensional)  "spaces."  Furthermore  these 
"intuitions"  are  a  priori  because  they  are  necessary ;  they  are  neces- 
sary because  they  are  supposed  to  cover  everything;  and  they  are 
supposed  to  cover  everything  once  more  because  they  are  absolutely 
homogeneous — a  uniform  scheme  which  nothing  can  escape.  Space 
and  time  are  for  Schopenhauer  and  Kant  intuitions  a  priori  in  so  far 
only  as  they  are  homogeneous  schemes,  to  be  placed  over  a  world 
of  immediate  images. 

Schopenhauer's  idea  of  time,  as  an  "intuition  a  priori"  is  the 
idea  of  a  homogeneous  scheme  to  be  placed  over  a  world  of  immediate 
images.  But  this  is  exactly  what  Bergson  calls  spatialized  time. 
Therefore  when  Bergson  contends  that  understanding  as  the  cor- 
relative of  matter  and  an  instrument  for  action  makes  use  not  only 
of  space  but  also  of  "spatialized  time,"  and  Schopenhauer  contends 
that  understanding  as  the  correlative  of  matter  and  an  instrument 
for  action  makes  use  not  only  of  space  but  also  of  time  as  an 
"intuition  a  priori"  they  mean  the  very  same  thing.  They  only  use 
a  different  vocabulary.  It  is  essential  for  both  that  space  and  time 
are  homogeneous  schemes  and  belong  to  understanding  as  means  of 
turning  immediate  images  into  matter  and  of  handling  matter  prac- 
tically. I  shall  very  soon  return  to  this  point. 

In  the  meantime  I  venture  to  sum  up  the  result,  thus  far  reached 
in  our  investigation,  in  the  statement  that  the  theories  of  Bergson 
and  Schopenhauer  with  regard  to  understanding,  matter,  space  and 
time  are  essentially  the  same.  And  since  half  of  the  entire  structure 
of  the  philosophies  of  these  two  men  is  constituted  by  those  theories, 
their  sameness  means  a  corresponding  sameness  of  half  that  struc- 
ture. 

*      *      * 

We  now  proceed  to  the  second  half  of  that  structure.  Opposed 
to  understanding  and  matter  there  stands  in  Schopenhauer's  philos- 


6O2  THE  MONIST. 

ophy  the  "will  to  live."  Opposed  to  understanding  and  matter  there 
stands  in  Bergson's  philosophy  a  "life-current"  the  "elan  vital" 

For  Bergson  as  well  as  for  Schopenhauer  the  world  of  under- 
standing is  only  a  world  of  "appearance."  It  is  not  true  reality,  but 
reality  prepared  for  action.  Hence,  by  understanding  we  are  not  in 
a  position  to  penetrate  into  the  essence  of  reality.  We  are  getting 
only  to  the  surfaces.  We  go  around  things,  but  cannot  enter  them. 

We  previously  noted  that  Bergson  used  a  simile  originally  used 
by  Schopenhauer.  Both  compare  understanding  to  a  "lantern"  which 
life  has  kindled  in  order  to  find  its  way  through  the  world.  Now 
we  discover  for  a  second  time  that  Bergson  and  Schopenhauer  use 
one  and  the  same  simile  in  precisely  the  same  way.  Schopenhauer 
writes  with  regard  to  the  inability  of  understanding  to  enter  life: 
"We  see  that  it  is  impossible  to  reach  the  inner  essence  of  things 
by  external  means ;  however  much  we  thus  investigate  we  find  only 
images  and  empty  names.  We  are  like  the  man  who  walks  around 
a  castle,  looks  in  vain  for  an  entrance  into  it  and  in  the  meantime 
sketches  its  walls"*  Compare  with  this  Bergson's  account  of  under- 
standing trying  in  vain  to  enter  life :  "It  is  like  the  work  of  an  artist/' 
he  writes,  "who  traveling  through  Paris  sketches  a  tower  of  Notre 
Dame. . .  .This  designer  replaces  the  true  inner  essence  of  the  object 
by  an  external  schematic  reproduction."* 

It  is  the  way  of  understanding  to  approach  its  objects  by  exter- 
nal means  only,  and  in  doing  so  it  tries  to  comprehend  the  life  inherent 
in  them  by  dividing  the  object  up  into  small  parts.  This,  however, 
is  in  vain.  Understanding  can  never  enter  life  in  this  way,  for 
the  only  true  way  of  coming  into  contact  with  life  is  by  feeling  it 
instinctively. 

Schopenhauer  illustrates  this  by  an  impressive  simile :  "Abstract 
knowledge,"  he  writes,  "compares  with  instinctive  feeling  as  a 
mosaic  compares  with  a  painting  by  Van  der  Werft  or  Denner ;  for 
however  nicely  the  mosaic  may  be  put  together,  the  outlines  between 
the  stones  remain  and  no  continual  transition  from  one  shade  of 
color  to  another  is  possible."6  Bergson  holds  the  same  view,  and  it 
is  surprising  that  in  another  context,  which  however  carries  the 
same  meaning,  he  again  uses  the  very  same  comparison  originally 
used  by  Schopenhauer.  "A  gifted  artist  paints  a  picture,"  he  writes. 

*  Werke,  I,  p.  150. 

'Bergson,  "Introduction  a  la  philosophic,"  Revue  de  metaphysique  et  de 
morale,  1903,  p.  10. 

6  Werke,  I,  p.  98  f . 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  603 

"We  could  imitate  his  picture  by  many  colored  stones.  The  more 
nicely  our  stones  are  put  together  the  more  manifold  and  different 
they  are  in  color,  the  better  we  shall  be  able  to  reproduce  their 
curves  and  shades.  But  we  should  need  an  infinite  number  of  in- 
finitely small  and  infinitely  differentiated  stones  in  order  to  reproduce 
the  picture  exactly."7 

The  idea  in  common,  expressed  by  Schopenhauer  and  Bergson  by 
exactly  the  same  simile,  is  that  life  cannot  be  perceived  by  external 
dissection  and  recomposition  but  only  by  instinctive  feeling.  This 
idea  is  of  decisive  importance  for  Bergson's  own  thought  as  well 
as  for  Schopenhauer's,  and  our  discovery  that  Bergson  and  Schopen- 
hauer use  the  same  similes  in  this  context  several  times  indicates 
that  their  coincidence  is  more  than  a  mere  curiosity. 

*       *       * 

For  Schopenhauer  as  for  Bergson  life  is  an  object  not  of  under- 
standing but  of  instinct.  In  fact,  Schopenhauer's  philosophy  might 
well  be  headed  "A  Study  in  Instinct"  as  well  as  Bergson's.  It  is 
therefore  quite  characteristic  for  both  of  these  thinkers  that  they 
are  so  greatly  concerned  with  instinct  as  a  biological  fact;  that  both 
of  them  pay  special  attention  to  insects,  because  in  them  instinct  is 
most  developed.  For  Bergson  as  for  Schopenhauer  life  is  not  only 
"the  object"  of  instinct.  It  would  be  more  just  to  say  that  to  them 
instinct  is  the  living  of  life ;  it  is  life  itself ;  it  is  really  as  it  is 
seen  directly,  while  the  knowledge  of  understanding  is  neither  life 
nor  reality  but  only  an  indirect  way  of  preparing  reality  for  practical 
use. 

For  Schopenhauer  as  for  Bergson  the  world  of  instinct  as  a 
world  of  reality  and  life  stands  opposed  to  the  world  of  under- 
standing as  a  world  of  appearance  and  death.  This  distinction  is 
of  greatest  importance  for  Schopenhauer's  philosophy  as  well  as 
for  Bergson's. 

So  Bergson  writes:  "If  one  compares  the  definitions  of  meta- 
physics and  of  the  Absolute  he  observes  that  all  philosophers  in 
spite  of  their  controversies  are  at  one  in  distinguishing  two  abso- 
lutely different  ways  of  knowing.  The  one  way  stops  at  the  relative ; 
the  other  penetrates  to  the  Absolute,  where  it  is  approachable .... 
The  Absolute  is  perceived  by  intuition,  everything  else  by  analysis. 
I  call  intuition  the  instinctive  sympathy  by  which  we  put  ourselves 
into  the  heart  of  an  object  in  order  to  unite  with  its  particular  in- 

7  Bergson,  loc.  cit.,  p.  2. 


604  THE  MONIST. 

expressible  essence."8  With  this  introduction  Bergson  plunges  the 
reader  into  what  he  considers  one  of  the  most  central  points  of  his 
philosophy. 

Precisely  the  same  way  of  "knowing  the  Absolute"  is  called  by 
Schopenhauer  "the  philosophical  truth  /car3  e£oxr?v"  for  his  own  sys- 
tem,9 and  Bergson  and  Schopenhauer  furthermore  agree  that  this 
central  truth  of  philosophy,  instinctive  knowledge  as  a  key  for  life, 
is  limited  at  first  to  the  knower's  own  being.  "There  is  at  least  one 
reality,"  Bergson  tells  us,  "which  we  all  perceive  from  the  inside 
by  intuition. . .  .that  is  we,  ourselves."10 

It  is  the  instinct  of  our  own  life  of  which  we  are  thus  aware ; 
but  unfortunately  this  instinct  is  the  only  reality  of  which  we  dis- 
pose directly.  We  have  to  transfer  our  own  living  instinct  to  the 
external  world  in  order  to  conceive  the  entire  life  of  the  universe. 
This  indirect  way  of  knowledge  set  forth  by  Professor  Bergson  is 
one  of  the  chief  principles  of  Schopenhauer's  philosophy.  What 
Schopenhauer  calls  "will"  is  nothing  else  but  what  Bergson  describes 
as  man's  own  life  immediately  experienced  by  instinctive  feeling  as 
the  "one  reality  which  we  all  perceive  from  the  inside,"  and  then 
transferred  to  the  external  world.  "Will"  is  a  determinate)  a  potion 
for  "what  we  immediately  experience  as  the  innermost  essence"  of 
our  own  life,  Schopenhauer  declares,*  and  furthermore  contends  that 
"to  him  who  knows  the  most  immediate  datum  of  consciousness  is 
will ....  this  conviction  will  become  the  key  for  a  knowledge  of  the 
inmost  essence  of  all  nature.  For  he  will  now  transfer  his  imme- 
diate experience  of  life  to  all  those  objects  which  are  not  given  to 
him  in  immediate  experience."11 

From  this  it  will  be  more  evident  why  Schopenhauer's  "will" 
and  Bergson's  elan  vital  are  precisely  the  same  thing.  The  reason 
is  that  both  are  brought  forth  by  the  same  "philosophical  truth  Kar 
e|o^v."  Both  "will"  and  elan  vital  are  philosophical  expressions 
for  instinctive  feeling  conceived  as  "the  living  of  life"  and  thence 

transferred  to  the  external  world. 

*       *       * 

In  this  world  of  "will"  or  elan  vital  the  problem  of  time  again 
appears.  We  have  already  dealt  with  this  problem  as  far  as  under- 

*  Bergson,  loc.  cit.,  p.  i. 

9  Werke,  I,  p.  154. 

10  Ibid.,  p.  4. 

*  Werke,  I,  p.  164. 
u  Werke,  I,  p.  162. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  605 

standing  is  involved  in  it;  we  have  now  to  deal  with  it  as  far  as  it 
extends  to  the  instinctive  feeling  of  life. 

In  this  latter  realm  the  problem  takes  up  the  form  of  an  an- 
tithesis. Life  as  instinctively  felt  is  according  to  Bergson,  duree 
reelle,  true  duration,  true  time,  and  to  Schopenhauer  it  is  "timeless." 
Here  Bergson  and  Schopenhauer  evidently  seem  to  contradict  each 
other,  but  as  in  our  former  discussion  the  contradiction  is  rather  in 
words  than  in  thought.  "True  duration"  means  for  Bergson  time 
freed  from  its  specialization.  "Timelessness"  means  for  Schopen- 
hauer time  freed  from  past  and  future.  It  means  "eternal  pres- 
ence." 

It  certainly  is  interesting  to  compare  this  conception  of  Schopen- 
hauer's with  Bergson's  duree  reelle.  If  you  ask  Bergson  why  we 
spatialize  time,  he  would  answer  that  we  do  so  in  order  to  bring 
past  and  future  to  the  same  level;  in  order  even  to  conceive  of  a 
future  and  of  a  past.  Hence  duree  reelle,  as  time  freed  from  its 
spatialization,  is  time  deprived  of  the  conception  of  past  and  future. 
But  that  is  precisely  what  Schopenhauer  calls  "timelessness."  If 
consistently  carried  out,  Bergson's  duree  reelle  viewed  from  the 
point  of  view  of  the  being  himself  who  exists  in  duree  reelle  is 
adequately  represented  only  by  Schopenhauer's  idea  of  "timeless- 
ness"  or  "eternal  presence."  Bergson  and  Schopenhauer,  contra- 
dicting each  other  in  their  expressions,  are  logically  bound  to  agree 
in  the  fact.  Schopenhauer's  "timelessness"  is  duree  reelle,  and  Berg- 
son's duree  reelle  ought  necessarily  be  conceived  as  timelessness. 

It  is  very  probable  that  Professor  Bergson  himself  would  con- 
tradict this  statement.  He  would  point  to  the  obvious  fact  that 
again  and  again  he  has  characterized  duree  reelle  as  involving  both 
past  and  future,  and  hence  as  something  entirely  different  from 
Schopenhauer's  timelessness.  This  is  very  true.  But  it  is  no  less 
true  that  if  meant  as  an  objection  to  Schopenhauer's  timelessness 
Bergson's  statement  would  be  very  inconsistent. 

There  are  two  points  of  view  which  should  not  be  confounded. 
Either  duree  reelle  is  viewed  by  an  observing  outsider  or  by  the 
being  himself  who  exists  in  duree  reelle.  An  outsider  can  realize 
that  what  this  being  experiences  involves  past  and  future,  the  being 
himself  however  can  not.  The  simple  reason  for  this  is  that  ac- 
cording to  Bergson's  own  doctrine  spatialization  of  time  is  necessary 
in  order  to  conceive,  however  vaguely,  of  any  past  or  any  future. 
But  spatialization  of  time  is  not  duree  reelle.  Hence  a  being  existing 
in  duree  reelle  does  not  realize  that  what  he  experiences  involves 


606  THE  MONIST. 

past  and  future.    He  does  not  know  either  "past"  or  "future."    He 
lives  in  timelessness,  because  he  lives  in  duree  reelle. 

Duree  reelle  or  "timelessness,"  viewed  from  the  point  of  view 
of  an  outsider,  leads  towards  the  conception  of  evolution.  Learning 
that  his  own  doctrine  of  evolution  was  very  much  like  that  of 
Schopenhauer,12  Professor  Bergson  thought  this  coincidence  "a  happy 
inconsistency"  on  the  part  of  Schopenhauer  because  of  the  latter's 
doctrine  of  "timelessness";  while  in  truth  the  apparently  missing 
coincidence  in  the  doctrine  of  "timelessness"  and  duree  reelle  was  an 
unhappy  inconsistency  on  the  part  of  Professor  Bergson.  There 
can  be  no  thought  of  evolution  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  being 
who  himself  lives  in  duree  reelle,  for  no  evolution  can  be  thought 
of  except  in  spatialized  time.  But,  in  full  compliance  with  the 
philosophy  of  Schopenhauer  as  well  as  of  Bergson  himself,  an  ob- 
serving outsider  may  see  a  very  obvious  evolution  where  the  being 
existing  in  duree  reelle  sees  "timelessness"  only. 

*       *       * 

I  return  from  the  problem  of  timelessness,  duree  reelle  and  evo- 
lution to  the  main  idea  of  Schopenhauer's  and  Bergson's  thought, 
to  their  "philosophical  truth  K<IT'  e^ox^v."  True  reality,  life,  is  the 
instinctive  feeling  of  one's  own  life-current  transferred  to  the  outer 
world  and  the  world  of  philosophy  as  a  world  of  instinct  and  life 
is  opposed  to  the  dead  world  of  understanding. 

This  philosophical  truth  icar'  C^GX^  is  founded  on  the  instinctive 
feeling  of  everybody's  own  life.  Hence  everybody  is  a  philosopher 
in  so  far  as  he  is  aware  of  his  own  life.  He  only  does  not  try  to 
express  his  feelings  in  conceptual  language.  Technical  philosophy 
therefore  is  essentially  constituted  of  everybody's  instinctive  and 
intuitive  feelings  enlarged,  systematized  and  changed  into  knowl- 
edge. 

Here  again  Schopenhauer  and  Bergson  express  themselves  in 
a  very  similar  way.  So  Schopenhauer  writes:  "By  intuition  or  in 
concrete  everybody  is  conscious  of  all  philosophical  truths,  but  to 
demonstrate  them  in  abstract  concepts  and  reflective  thought  is  the 
business  of  philosophy."13  Compare  with  this  Bergson's  words: 
"Every  lasting  system  of  philosophy  is  enlivened  by  intuition  at 

"Compare  the  very  interesting  article  of  Prof.  Arthur  O.  Lovejoy  of 
Johns  Hopkins  University  in  The  Monist,  XXI,  pp.  216  ff. 

18  Werke,  I,  p.  491. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  607 

least  in  some  parts.    Dialectic  is  necessary  to  demonstrate  intuition, 
to  mirror  it  in  concepts  and  to  communicate  it  to  others."14 

The  similarity  between  Bergson's  and  Schopenhauer's  idea  is 
striking  even  in  its  expression.  Indeed  both  philosophies  belong 
to  the  same  well-known  type  of  thought  that  calls  itself  "intuitive." 
Every  intuitive  philosophy  somewhat  despises  abstract  concepts.15 
Still  when  intuition  becomes  a  philosophy  abstract  concepts  are 
needed,  and  they  are  generously  used  in  the  writings  of  our  two 
thinkers  in  spite  of  their  contention  that  nobody  enters  the  Absolute 
in  this  way.  The  gulf  between  understanding  and  instinct,  theoret- 
ically established,  is  practically  bridged  by  philosophic  discourse. 
There  the  work  of  understanding  is  enlivened  by  instinct,  and  the 
life  of  instinct  is  expressed  in  terms  of  understanding.  None  the 
less  instinct  and  understanding  remain  theoretically  entirely  different 
for  both  Bergson  and  Schopenhauer,  and  it  is  not  their  difference 
but  their  combination  which  by  the  latter  is  considered  as  the  "riddle 
of  the  universe." 

This  riddle  of  the  universe,  and  corresponding  to  it  the  "philo- 
sophical truth  Kar*  eloxV  of  Bergson  and  Schopenhauer,  fairly  sums 
up  what  I  wanted  to  state  in  this  part  of  my  paper,  namely,  that 
these  two  philosophies  are  no  less  similar  in  the  second  half  of  their 
structure  than  they  were  in  its  first  half.  A  theory  of  understand- 
ing common  to  both  constitutes  the  first  half,  a  theory  of  instinctive 
life  as  opposed  to  understanding  no  less  common  to  both  constitutes 
the  second  half  of  their  systems.  Thus  the  entire  structure  of  the 
thought  of  both  is  identical  in  its  main  outlines. 

*       *       * 

It  would  be  possible  to  show  how  in  some  corollaries  further  in- 
structive similarities  between  Bergson's  and  Schopenhauer's  philos- 
ophy spring  up  from  that  main  identity. 

I  shall  allude  only  to  Bergson's  theory  of  evolution,  which,  as 
Prof.  Arthur  O.  Love  joy  has  pointed  out  in  his  very  interesting 
paper,  exhibits  a  striking  similarity  to  Schopenhauer's  evolution- 
ism.16 Bergson's  doctrine  of  the  unity  of  life  is  strangely  similar  to 
Schopenhauer's  doctrine  of  the  unity  of  will.  For  both  thinkers 
this  unity  forms  the  basis  of  their  evolutionism.  On  the  other  hand 
it  has  been  pointed  out  in  this  paper  that  Bergson's  theory  of  dis- 

14  Bergson,  Evolution  creatrice,  p.  259;  "Introduction  a  la  philosophic," 
Revue  de  metaphysique  et  de  morale,  1903,  p.  4. 

"  The  only  true  language  of  intuition  is  silence. 
18  See  note  12. 


608  THE  MONIST. 

section  as  opposed  to  the  unity  of  life  goes  back  also  to  Schopen- 
hauer. 

Another  point  of  similarity  is  to  be  found  in  the  theory  by 
which  Bergson  and  Schopenhauer  explain  laughter.  Both  find  its 
main  cause  in  the  sudden  perception  of  a  discord  between  torpid 
understanding  and  flexible  life. 

In  their  theory  of  art  both  lay  stress  on  the  artist's  power  to  do 
away  with  the  pragmatistic  narrowness  of  understanding  and  to 
bring  man  into  immediate  contact  with  life  itself. 

And  Schopenhauer's  theory  of  freedom  although  apparently  very 
different  from  that  of  Bergson  is  likewise  founded  upon  the  idea  that 
causality  exists  only  in  the  realm  of  understanding  and  appearance, 
while  life  in  itself,  will,  is  free  and  may  manifest  its  freedom  to  the 
living  being — although  the  realization  of  this  freedom  is  conceived 
very  differently  by  Schopenhauer  and  Bergson,  the  former  being  far 

more  consistent  in  this  respect  as  in  others. 

*      *      * 

Professor  Bergson  is  by  no  means  a  consistent  thinker.  On  the 
other  hand  it  is  well  known  that  although  more  consistent  than  Berg- 
son, Schopenhauer  too  has  justly  been  accused  of  great  inconsistency. 
This  is  one  of  the  chief  reasons  why  in  spite  of  their  striking  simi- 
larity the  philosophies  of  Schopenhauer  and  Bergson  differ  widely 
in  more  than  one  respect.  Schopenhauer's  Kantianism  and  Neo- 
Platonism,  which  are  incongruous  with  the  rest  of  his  system,  are 
happily  avoided  by  Bergson.  On  the  other  hand  Bergson's  incon- 
sistencies with  regard  to  his  activism  and  the  confusion  of  his  ter- 
minology with  regard  to  time  and  some  minor  points  are  avoided 
by  Schopenhauer.  That  Schopenhauer  was  more  pessimistic  than 
Bergson  is  of  much  consequence  for  the  external  appearance  but  of 
comparatively  little  consequence  for  the  inner  structure  of  both  sys- 
tems. 

Important,  however,  is  the  fact  that  Schopenhauer  is  far  more 
systematic  than  Bergson.  His  philosophy  is  an  attempt  to  furnish 
an  all-embracing  Weltanschauung  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  will 
to  live  and  its  servant,  understanding.  Bergson's  philosophy  con- 
sists rather  of  several  specific  investigations,  more  or  less  loosely 
connected.  That  is  the  reason  why  on  the  whole  Schopenhauer's  phi- 
losophy is  much  more  imposing  and  in  almost  all  details  much 
richer  than  Bergson's  thought,  while  Bergson  has  the  advantage  of 
being  less  dogmatic  and  possibly  still  more  stimulating  than  Schopen- 
hauer. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  609 

As  to  elegance  of  style,  figurative  language  and  happy  choice 
of  comparisons  no  modern  philosopher  can  equal  either  Schopen- 
hauer or  Bergson.  They  rival  each  other  and  both  are  unsurpassed. 
However,  it  seems  to  me  that  Professor  Bergson's  style,  especially 
his  figurative  language  and  his  predilection  for  comparisons,  is  not 
quite  independent  of  the  stilistic  habits  of  Schopenhauer.  Our  dis- 
covery that  Bergson  uses  three  similes  originally  used  by  Schopen- 
hauer is  a  strong  indication  in  that  direction.  Bergson  carries  a 
stilistic  habit  of  Schopenhauer  to  an  extreme;  but  this  is  only  a 
symptom  of  a  general  feature  of  Bergson's  style  which  is  far  more 
onesided  and  far  less  varied,  but  at  the  same  time  still  more  sur- 
prising and  stimulating,  than  Schopenhauer's.  Thus  the  differences 
of  thought  in  the  two  men  are  peculiarly  mirrored  in  the  differences 

of  their  style. 

*       *       * 

This  leads  to  the  question  as  to  the  psychological  background 
for  the  similarity  between  Bergson's  and  Schopenhauer's  thought. 
When  Bergson  worked  out  his  thought  did  he  plagiarize  Schopen- 
hauer? The  only  answer  to  this  very  natural  question  of  a  layman 
in  the  history  of  philosophy  would  be  an  unmistakable  "Certainly 
not!" 

Personally  I  have  good  reasons  to  contend  that  Professor  Berg- 
son is  not  even  aware  of  most  of  these  similarities,  and  very  likely 
never  was.  He  himself  is  probably  inclined  to  think  that  most  of 
what  he  actually  took  from  Schopenhauer  is  his  own  original  thought 
— original  in  the  popular  sense  of  "creation." 

In  fact,  however,  Bergson's  thought  appears  to  be  "original" 
not  in  the  popular,  but  only  in  the  Bergsonian  sense  of  creation. 
Popular  creation  is  creation  out  of  nothing;  Bergsonian  creation  is 
the  past  prolonged  into  the  future.  For  Bergson  all  life  is  creative 
because  it  is  saturated  with  the  life  that  has  preceded  it.  Bergson's 
own  philosophy  certainly  is  Bergsonian  life  par  excellence.  Hence  it 
is  creative,  because  it  is  saturated  with  preceding  life ;  and  I  contend 
that  the  preceding  life  with  which  it  is  saturated  is  Schopenhauer's 
philosophy. 

This  is  not  very  difficult  to  prove,  for  Bergson  himself  tells  us 
that  he  formerly  studied  Schopenhauer's  philosophy  closely.  More- 
over, when  Bergson  was  at  the  most  impressionable  and  decisive 
stage  of  his  mental  development  a  Schopenhauer  craze  was  preva- 
lent in  France,  and  Schopenhaueristes  were  seen  even  in  literature 
and  society.  Finally,  Bergson's  teacher  Ravaisson  was  a  follower 


6lO  THE  MONIST. 

of  Schelling.  Indeed  some  residua  of  Schelling's  philosophy — espe- 
cially with  regard  to  his  theory  of  matter — are  easily  discoverable  in 
Bergson's  thought.  But  what  is  still  more  important  for  our  in- 
vestigation, there  was  no  better  way  to  prepare  Bergson  for  Schopen- 
hauer's philosophy  than  by  a  knowledge  of  Schelling,  out  of  whose 
thought  Schopenhauer's  own  ideas  emerged,  just  as  to-day  there  is 
perhaps  no  better  way  to  prepare  a  mind  for  Bergson's  philosophy 
than  by  a  knowledge  of  Schopenhauer,  out  of  whose  thought  Berg- 
son's  ideas  have  emerged. 

*       *       * 

All  this  leads  us  back  to  where  we  started.  The  history  of 
philosophy  is  like  one  of  the  ancestral  galleries  in  ancient  European 
castles.  Certain  family  traits  reappear  again  and  again  in  the  struc- 
ture of  philosophical  systems  and  Henri  Bergson's  philosophy  bears 
the  family  traits  of  Schopenhauer's  "World  as  Will  and  Idea." 

But  Schopenhauer's  own  philosophy  shows  family  traits  as  well. 
It  emerged  out  of  the  philosophy  of  Schelling  and  the  general  trend 
of  German  romantic  thought  in  the  early  19th  century,  and  German 
romanticism  again  owed  a  great  deal  to  Herder  and  Goethe.  Indeed 
I  know  a  passage  by  Goethe  which  contains  Bergson's  entire  thought 
in  a  nutshell.  Using  "reason"  for  "intuition"  according  to  the  ter- 
minology of  his  time  Goethe  says  to  Eckermann:  "The  godhead  is 
active  in  the  living,  but  not  in  the  dead;  it  works  in  the  growing, 
the  developing,  but  not  in  the  finished,  the  torpid.  Therefore  reason 
with  its  tendency  for  the  Divine  has  to  do  with  the  growing,  the 
living;  understanding  with  the  finished,  the  torpid  that  it  may  use 
it  for  practical  purposes."17  Change  Goethe's  terminology  into  the 
language  of  Bergson,  and  the  thought  expressed  by  Goethe  is  almost 
as  Bergsonian  as  Bergson's  own. 

This  Bergson-Schopenhauer-Schelling-Goethe-Herder  type  of 
philosophy  could  easily  be  traced  back  to  the  old  German  mysticism 
and  still  further  back  to  the  ancient  philosophy  of  the  Vedanta,  with 
both  of  which  Schopenhauer  and  most  of  his  German  predecessors 
knew  that  their  own  thought  was  more  or  less  closely  connected. 

Viewed  from  its  first  beginning  to  its  present  stage  the  develop- 
ment of  this  type  of  thought  goes  on  exactly  in  the  way  which 
Bergson  himself  terms  evolution  creatrice.  As  a  living  process  it 
enters  the  thought  of  a  philosopher  in  the  shape  last  given  to  it  by 
the  preceding  generation.  As  a  living  process  it  is  itself  "creative," 
i.  e.,  it  assumes  a  new  shape  different  from  what  it  had  before ;  and 

17  Conversations  with  Eckermann,  Febr.  13,  1829. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  6ll 

in  the  brain  of  the  following  generation  it  certainly  will  change 
again  as  a  creative  power. 

Bergson's  philosophy  proceeds  from  an  elan  vital  of  thought. 
This  explains  why  it  is  saturated  with  the  past  and,  as  we  may  hope, 
pregnant  with  the  future.  The  past  with  which  it  is  saturated,  how- 
ever, is  neither  pragmatism  nor  any  American  nor  English  philos- 
ophy, for  all  these  mean  typical  work  of  "understanding,"  while 
for  Bergson  philosophy  begins  where  understanding  ceases.  The 
elan  vital  in  Bergson's  own  philosophy  is  German  and  characteristic 
of  the  close  affinity  between  German  and  French  philosophy — an 
affinity  which  may  be  traced  back  all  through  the  history  of  human 
thought.  In  former  ages  the  influence  of  French  thought  on  Ger- 
many preponderated  over  the  influence  of  German  thought  on  France. 
Since  the  beginning  of  the  nineteenth  century  it  is  the  influence  of 
German  thought  on  France  which  has  preponderated  because  there 
was  a  feeling  that  the  elan  vital  of  German  thought  is  creative  and 
pregnant  with  a  future.  Never  was  its  creative  power  developed 
with  more  splendor  and  force  than  in  Henri  Bergson's  philosophy. 

GUNTHER  JACOBY. 

THE  UNIVERSITY  OF  GREIFSWALD. 


HENRI  POINCARE:  OBITUARY. 

On  July  17,  1912,  the  world  lost  the  great  French  mathema- 
tician whom  Karl  Weierstrass — one  of  the  greatest  mathematicians 
of  the  nineteenth  century — when  writing  to  Sophie  Kowalevsky, 
specially  singled  out  as  one  of  the  most  eminent  of  the  school  of 
younger  French  mathematicians.1 

Jules  Henri  Poincare  was  born  at  Nancy  on  April  29,  1854. 
He  came  of  a  family  of  which  various  members  have  risen  to  emi- 
nence. His  father  was  professor  in  the  Faculty  of  Medicine  at 
Nancy,  and  wrote,  among  other  works,  on  neurology  at  a  time  at 
which  such  researches  were  only  pursued  by  a  small  number  of 
scientific  men.  An  uncle,  Antoni  Poincare,  wrote  on  meterology; 
and,  of  his  two  sons,  one  is  M.  Raymond  Poincare,  the  present 
President  of  the  Ministerial  Council,  and  the  other  is  M.  Lucien 
Poincare,  who  is  Director  of  Secondary  Education  and  Minister  of 
Public  Instruction.  Henri  Poincare's  only  sister  married  M.  Emile 

1Cf.  G.  Mittag-Leffler,  Compte  rendu  du  deuxitme  congres  international 
des  mathematiciens  tenu  a  Paris 7900,  Paris,  1902,  pp.  145-148. 


6l2  THE  MONIST. 

Boutroux,  the  distinguished  philosopher,  and  their  son,  M.  Pierre 
Boutroux,  is  a  well-known  mathematician. 

Henri  Poincare  was  precocious,  intellectually,  and  entered  the 
Ecole  Polytechnique  in  1873,  and  in  1875  the  School  of  Mines  as 
engineering  pupil ;  in  1879  he  gained  the  degree  of  Doctor  of  Mathe- 
matical Sciences  at  the  University  of  Paris;  in  the  same  year  he 
joined  the  Service  of  Mines  as  engineer;  in  1881  he  became  pro- 
fessor at  the  Faculty  of  Sciences  in  Paris;  in  1887  he  was  elected 
a  member  of  the  Academy  of  Sciences;  and  in  1908  he  was  elected 
one  of  the  forty  "immortals"  of  the  French  Academy. 

A  biography  of  Poincare  and  a  bibliography  of  his  works  has 
been  published  by  Ernest  Lebon.2  Poincare's  first  original  researches 
were  in  pure  mathematics.  In  1880  the  Academy  of  Sciences  pro- 
posed the  theory  of  differential  equations  as  the  subject  of  the  great 
prize.  Poincare  sent  in  a  sketchy  memoir  with  the  title  "Non 
inultus  premor" — that  of  the  town  of  Nancy — which  did  not  gain 
the  prize  but  which  Charles  Hermite  mentioned  encouragingly  in 
his  report.  From  the  beginning  of  1881  the  subject — the  integration 
of  certain  linear  differential  equations — was  developed  with  sur- 
prising genius  and  rapidity  in  a  series  of  papers  presented  weekly 
to  the  Academy  of  Sciences.  Weierstrass,  who  admired  these  papers 
so  warmly,  thought  it  a  pity  that  Frenchmen  published  their  dis- 
coveries in  a  succession  of  little  papers.  But  surely  the  psychological 
interest  is  heightened  by  this  mode  of  publication.  We  know  that 
Poincare  worked  almost  subconsciously,  and  often  had  no  idea  of 
what  he  was  going  to  discover.  Gauss's  motto  was,  Pauca  sed 
matura,  and  even  now  almost  every  publication  of  his  is  an  almost 
perfect  and  complete  classic ;  and  yet  how  greatly  do  we  feel  the  need 
of  some  indication  as  to  how  these  discoveries  grew.  Weierstrass 
reminds  us  in  many  respects  of  Gauss.  His  works,  too,  were  never 
quickly  published,  and  very  many  important  things  he  found  or 
views  he  held  were  either  not  published  at  all,  or  only  long  after 
he  announced  them,  and  then  by  his  pupils.  The  case  is  different 
with  Poincare.  One  of  the  many  reasons  for  which  he  will  live  is 
because  he  has  made  it  possible  for  us  to  understand  him  as  well  as 
to  admire  him. 

Poincare's  name  is  associated,  for  the  pure  mathematician,  with 
the  "Fuchsian,"  "Thetafuchsian,"  and  "Zetafuchsian"  functions.  We 
now  call  them,  after  Felix  Klein,  "automorphic"  functions.  But  we 


Paris 


a Henri  Poincare:  biographie,  bibliographie  analytique  des  ecrits;  26.  ed., 
s,  Gauthier-Villars,  1912  (collection  "Savants  du  Jour"). 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  613 

can  only  refer  to  his  other  researches  on  the  theory  of  functions  and 
his  allied  work  on  the  theory  of  numbers,  and  will  now  turn  to  his 
works  on  astronomy  and  physics. 

Poincare's  investigations  on  the  form  taken  by  a  gravitating 
mass  of  fluid  in  rotation  (1885-1901)  led  him  to  interesting  theories 
on  the  parting  of  the  earth  and  moon  and  the  formation  of  variable 
stars.  His  researches  on  the  stability  of  the  solar  system,  which  con- 
sisted in  the  revision  of  Laplace's  calculations  and  the  carrying  of 
them  to  a  higher  order  of  approximation,  showed  that  Laplace's 
theory  of  1784  was  quite  just.  These  and  other  results  are  con- 
tained in  Poincare's  three  volumes  on  the  new  methods  of  celestial 
mechanics.3  Here  we  must  also  refer  to  his  works  on  the  tides  and 
on  the  problem  of  three  bodies.  On  mathematical  physics,  Poincare 
published  many  volumes  of  lectures  given  at  the  University  of  Paris 
and  elsewhere  on  light,  electricity — including  the  theory  of  Maxwell 
— capillarity,  vortices,  potential,  thermodynamics,  the  theory  of  the 
conduction  of  heat,  elasticity,  and  the  theory  of  wireless  telegraphy. 
Besides  these,  his  lectures  on  the  calculus  of  probabilities  and  on 
various  subjects  in  celestial  mechanics  have  been  published. 

Some  very  interesting  psychological  and  physical  details  about 
Poincare  were  published  in  1900  by  Dr.  Toulouse  as  the  second 
volume — the  first  was  chiefly  occupied  by  a  study  of  Emile  Zola — 
of  his  Enquete  medico-psychologique  sur  la  superiorite  intellectuelle* 
The  help  given  to  the  scientific  answering  of  the  question :  "Le  genie 
est-il  une  nevrose?"  by  such  studies  is,  of  course,  immense;  but 
most  of  my  readers  are  more  concerned  with  the  qualities  associated 
with  the  great  mathematical  capacities  of  a  man  who  took  such  a 
keen  interest  in  questions  on  the  border-line  between  mathematics 
and  philosophy.5  It  is  impossible  to  read  Dr.  Toulouse's  book  with- 
out gaining  a  very  vivid  picture  of  the  personality  of  Henri  Poin- 
care. It  is  always  deeply  interesting  to  read  authentic  accounts  of 
the  methods  of  work  of  mathematicians,  and  for  some  years  past, 
MM.  H.  Fehr,  Th.  Flournoy  and  E.  Claparede  have  conducted  an 
inquiry  on  this  subject  in  the  columns  of  L' Enseignement  mathe- 
matique.  Poincare  himself,  in  a  well-known  article  published  in 
1908,  has  made  some  striking  observations  on  his  own  process  of 
mathematical  discovery.  And  we  must,  I  think,  bear  in  mind,  when 

8  Les  Methodes  nouvelles  de  la  Mecanique  celeste,  Paris,  1892-1899. 
*  Henri  Poincare\  Paris,  Ernest  Flammarion. 

8  Poincare's  work  in  this  direction  is  well  known  to  readers  of  The  Monist 
by  the  translations  of  George  Bruce  Halsted. 


614  THE  MONIST. 

reading  Poincare's  articles  on  the  logic  of  mathematics,  that  they 
are  the  work  of  a  man  who  was  primarily — perhaps  almost  exclu- 
sively— interested  in  the  faculties  of  invention.  When  mathematical 
logicians  asserted  that  the  whole  of  mathematics  follows  by  logical 
principles  alone  from  concepts  which  can  be  logically  defined  and 
from  the  primitive  propositions  of  logic  alone,  Poincare  and  many 
other  mathematicians  objected  that  "intuition"  was  left  out  of  ac- 
count. There  is  a  great  likelihood  that  this  is  not  really  Kantianism 
in  mathematics ;  only  phrases  make  it  seem  so.  Kant  clearly  recog- 
nized the  distinction  between  the  question  as  to  whether  a  truth  B 
is  logically  implied  by  a  truth  A  and  that  as  to  whether  B  is  dis- 
covered by  a  certain  person  who  starts  from  the  premise  A  alone  and 
uses  only  purely  logical  considerations.  The  mathematical  logicians 
do  not  deny  to  the  seeker  of  truth  either  genius  or  the  creative  power 
— if  such  exist — of  the  artist ;  they  are  concerned  with  an  epistemo- 
logical  question,  and  psychological  objections  are  irrelevant  there. 
The  case  is  analogous  to  this:  If  someone  were  to  point  out  that 
the  properties  of  logarithms  are  simple  consequences  of  the  con- 
ception of  one  number  as  a  power  of  another,  he  would  not  be  con- 
futed by  the  remark  that  Napier  did  not  invent  logarithms  in  that 
way;  or  again,  it  is  not  relevant  to  the  student  of  Keats's  poetry, 
as  such,  to  know  what  porridge  John  Keats  ate. 

If  this  interpretation  of  the  attitude  of  the  "creative"  mathema- 
ticians is  correct,  their  position  with  respect  to  mathematical  logic 
is  easily  explained.  That  the  interpretation  is  correct  seems  sup- 
ported by  Poincare's  last  controversial  work  on  mathematical  logic 
which  he  gave  this  year  as  a  lecture  to  London  University,  and  which 
has  just  been  printed  in  Sciential  In  the  previous  discussions  on  the 
use  of  the  infinite  in  mathematics,  in  which  Poincare  joined,  each  side 
kept  on  repeating  the  same  arguments.  There  seems,  in  fact,  a 
fundamental  difference  in  mentality  among  mathematicians.  Some, 
whom  Poincare  called  "pragmatists,"  believe  that  the  infinite  is 
derived  from  the  finite,  and  all  verification  and  all  definition  is  per- 
formed with  a  finite  number  of  words ;  others,  the  "Cantorians," 
believe  that  there  are  objects  and  truths  which  cannot  be  defined  or 
demonstrated  in  a  finite  number  of  words.  The  Cantorians  are 
realists  and  believe  that  the  truth  of  a  proposition  does  not  depend 
on  its  verification  by  us.  It  is  not  difficult  to  place  Poincare,  on  the 

6  "La  Logique  de  rinfini,"  Scientia  (Rivista  di  Sciensa),  July,  1912,  pp. 
i-n. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  615 

grounds  of  some  of  his  writings,  among  those  whom  he  not  inap- 
propriately calls  "pragmatists." 

When  Poincare  was  five  years  old,  he  had  a  severe  attack  of 
diphtheria,  and  partial  paralysis.  All  this  made  him  rather  weak  for 
a  long  time,  and  perhaps  was  the  origin  of  his  lifelong  clumsiness. 
Of  his  absence  of  mind,  many  stories  are  told.  Once  during  a  walk, 
he  was  suddenly  surprised  to  find  a  wicker  bird-cage  in  his  hand. 
He  had  unconsciously  removed  it  from  a  wayside  stall. 

As  regards  religion,  at  the  moment  of  his  first  communion  he 
was  a  believer ;  then  belief  left  him  gradually,  and,  from  the  age  of 
eighteen  he  was  a  sceptic.  In  politics  he  was  a  republican ;  he  held 
to  the  principle  of  personal  property ;  he  believed  in  political  equality 
and  the  political  rights  of  women, — but  here  he  feared  clerical  in- 
fluence. 

In  mathematics,  he  cannot  be  said  to  belong  to  any  school.  In 
a  short  life  not  without  physical  drawbacks,  he  has,  by  regular  work, 
produced  about  500  writings — some  of  them  of  the  very  first  order. 

PHILIP  E.  B.  JOURDAIN. 

THE  LODGE,  GIRTON,  CAMBRIDGE,  ENGLAND. 


HENRI  POINCARE:  AN  APPRECIATION. 

The  foremost  of  Frenchmen  is  no  more.  When  Laplace  was 
asked  to  name  the  greatest  German  mathematician  he  answered, 
"Pfaff."  "But  how  about  Gauss?"  said  the  inquirer.  "Ah,"  replied 
Laplace,  "he  is  the  greatest  of  all  mathematicians."  Similarly  we 
might  modify  our  first  statement  and  declare  that  the  foremost  of 
all  men  is  no  more.  For  on  July  17,  having  apparently  recovered 
almost  completely  from  a  surgical  operation  undergone  only  a  few 
days  before,  Henri  Poincare,  while  dressing  himself  in  the  morning, 
was  suddenly  smitten  with  an  embolism  and  fell  dying  in  the  arms 
of  his  wife.  While  the  delegates  of  learning  from  all  quarters  of  the 
globe  were  assembling  in  London  to  celebrate  the  250th  anniversary 
of  the  Royal  Society,  instantly  the  brightest  star  in  the  galaxy  of  the 
sciences  was  eclipsed  forever.  The  sad  intelligence  was  at  once 
flashed  around  the  world,  but  the  details  as  set  forth  in  the  Paris 
journals  of  the  18th  are  but  lately  at  hand. 

Commanding  the  homage,  and  admiration  of  all,  so  generous, 
so  pure-hearted,  so  noble-minded  was  Poincare  that  he  aroused  the 
envy  and  jealousy  of  none.  If  "Freedom  shrieked  when  Kosciusko 
fell,"  with  far  more  propriety  may  universal  Science,  may  Philosophy 


6l6  THE  MONIST. 

herself,  weep  at  the  passing  of  her  illustrious  son.  For  Poincare 
was  not  a  mere  specialist,  an  isolated  summit  of  technical  learning, 
but  rather  a  mountain  range  of  knowledge.  His  Andean  intellect 
traversed  the  whole  continent  of  science.  In  physics,  in  mathematics, 
in  astronomy,  in  logic,  in  philosophy  even,  he  strode  from  peak  to 
peak  in  the  heights  of  thought,  and  wherever  his  feet  touched,  there 
was  a  blaze  enkindled.  His  compatriots  say  that  France  has  borne 
no  equal  in  a  hundred  years,  not  since  d'Alembert  and  Laplace.  To 
a  foreigner  it  may  be  questionable  whether  the  limit  may  not  be 
pushed  much  further  back,  even  to  the  days  of  Descartes.  For  while 
the  mind  of  Poincare  did  indeed  cast  off  no  single  orb  of  thought 
to  match  at  once  in  largeness  and  in  luster  the  Mecanique  celeste, 
or  still  more  the  Theorie  analytique  des  probabilites,  yet  it  has  studded 
the  firmament  of  exact  science  with  a  host  of  splendors.  Scarcely 
if  at  all  inferior  to  Laplace  or  even  to  Lagrange  as  analyst,  as  geom- 
eter, as  physicist,  as  astronomer,  Poincare  was  what  they  were  not 
— he  was  a  logician  of  the  first  order  and  a  philosopher,  profound, 
penetrating,  and  spiritual.  Nor  was  this  all;  for  his  genius  in  ex- 
position allied  him  with  Clifford  and  brought  him  into  livelier  sym- 
pathy with  the  lay  intellect  than  almost  any  of  his  peers  in  the  realm 
of  pure  science,  while  his  fine  artistic  nature  and  literary  sense  ex- 
pressed themselves  in  a  style  at  once  clear  and  concise,  nervous, 
vivid,  picturesque  and  animated.  As  subtle  as  Hume,  as  compre- 
hensive as  Helmholtz,  he  was  least  of  all  a  dry-as-dust  savant;  the 
keenest  of  logicians,  he  did  not  disdain  the  graces  of  rhetoric,  but 
poured  out  for  his  fellows  the  divine  draughts  of  his  thought  in 
golden  goblets  of  speech. 

It  was  not,  however,  as  mathematical  physicist,  as  analyst  of 
Fuchsian  functions,  not  as  student  of  the  stability  of  the  solar  system, 
not  as  discoverer  of  unsuspected  figures  of  equilibrium,  not  as  master 
of  metageometry,  not  as  preeminent  logician  of  science,  not  as  any 
nor  as  all  of  these,  that  Poincare  rendered  his  highest  service  to 
humanity.  It  is  his  supreme  merit  to  have  recognized  explicitly  the 
inalienable  rights  of  the  human  spirit,  to  have  opposed  firm  as  Gib- 
raltar the  rising  tide  of  naturalism  and  the  pride  of  knowledge 
which,  intoxicated  with  the  triumphs  of  physical  science  and  its  ap- 
plications, refuses  to  see  any  mystery  beyond  sense  remaining  in  the 
world,  and  boldly  aspires  by  means  of  mind  to  pull  down  mind  from 
its  throne  and  to  reduce  the  universe  to  a  molecular  maelstrom,  to 
a  wisp  of  granulated  ether.  When  Napoleon  asked  Laplace  about 
having  written  so  great  a  book  without  once  naming  the  name  of  God 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  617 

therein  the  savant  replied,  "Sire,  I  have  no  need  of  that  hypothesis." 
Lagrange,  a  finer  spirit,  on  hearing  of  this  commented:  "But  it  is 
a  beautiful  hypothesis  that  explains  many  things."  In  his  famous 
mot  Laplace  has  declared  his  kingship  and  at  the  same  time  defined 
his  kingdom.  True,  in  the  realm  of  matter  he  had  no  need  of  the 
beautiful  hypothesis ;  in  the  kingdom  of  causality,  of  mass  and  mo- 
tion, there  is  no  purpose,  no  reason,  and  hence  no  need  of  God,  the 
Reason  of  all.  But  Poincare  saw  through  all  the  phantasies  of 
"scientists,"  as  the  astronomer  sees  through  the  nebula  in  Orion, 
and  beheld  far  behind  the  phenomena  of  time  and  space  the  eternal 
realities  of  self  and  of  soul;  while  peering  into  the  processes  of 
physical  nature  deeper  even  than  Laplace  himself,  he  never  forgot 
that  they  are  after  all  an  unsubstantial  pageant,  that 

"On  earth  is  nothing  great  but  man, 
In  man  is  nothing  great  but  mind." 

So  he  became  in  a  sense  the  moderator  of  the  assembly  of  the 
sciences.  As  no  other  living  man  he  could  say,  "Thus  far  and  no 
further ;"  for  he  spake  as  one  having  authority.  Even  the  Germans, 
who  are  seldom  over-quick  to  acknowledge  the  hegemony  of  others 
in  the  ranks  of  thought,  forgot  all  national  and  racial  prejudices  in 
the  presence  of  Poincare  and  freely  declared  him  to  be  "the  first 
authority  of  this  age"  (die  erste  Autoritat  von  dieser  Zeit). 

The  savant  closed  his  eyes  at  the  age  of  fifty-eight  in  the  full 
flush  of  his  powers,  at  the  fever-heat  of  his  intellectual  activity. 
What  more  he  might  have  done,  who  knows?  But  assuredly  his 
mantle  will  fall  upon  worthy  if  not  upon  equal  shoulders ;  in  the 
paths  he  has  broken  there  will  follow  increasing  throngs.  It  is  our 
human  form  of  speech  to  deplore  an  irreparable  loss.  But  in  some 
larger,  deeper  and  higher,  though  indefinable,  sense  there  is  perhaps 
only  gain  forevermore. 

"One  accent  of  the  Holy  Ghost 
The  heedless  world  hath  never  lost." 

Le  roi  est  mort :  vive  le  roi.  Poincare  is  dead :  but  deathless  is 
Poincare. 

WILLIAM  BENJAMIN  SMITH. 
TULANE  UNIVERSITY. 


6l8  THE  MONIST. 

THE   CAPTURE   THEORY   OF   COSMICAL   EVOLUTION 

CONFIRMED  BY  THE  LATEST  RESEARCHES  ON 

THE   ORIGIN    OF    STAR    CLUSTERS. 

Introductory  Remarks. 

It  is  a  very  remarkable  fact  that  since  the  epoch  of  Sir  William 
Herschel  little  serious  consideration  has  been  given  to  the  origin  of 
star  clusters,  until  within  the  last  few  years.  Accordingly  the 
thoughtful  suggestions  thrown  out  by  that  unrivaled  man  long 
proved  largely  if  not  entirely  barren  of  fruitful  results  for  the  de- 
velopment of  a  science  of  cosmogony,  because  his  early  ideas  were 
lost  sight  of  or  forgotten.  We  have  labored  under  a  strange  delu- 
sion, of  preferring  the  theories  of  Laplace  to  those  of  Herschel, 
but  have  at  last  found  the  way  from  darkness  to  light,  from  error 
to  truth.  And  it  happens  that  of  all  the  investigations  yet  made  in 
cosmogony  those  relating  to  the  neglected  subject  of  star  clusters 
are  the  most  convincing  and  least  open  to  objection. 

In  a  paper  entitled  "Dynamical  Theory  of  the  Globular  Clusters 
and  of  the  Clustering  Power  Inferred  by  Herschel  from  the  Ob- 
served Figures  of  Sidereal  Systems  of  High  Order,"  recently  com- 
municated to  the  American  Philosophical  Society  held  at  Philadel- 
phia, and  just  published  in  the  Proceedings  of  that  illustrious 
society,  I  have  examined  the  whole  problem  of  the  origin  of  clusters 
in  a  somewhat  exhaustive  manner.  By  the  use  of  mathematical 
methods  of  rigorous  character,  I  was  able  to  develop  the  most  con- 
vincing proofs  that  these  aggregations  of  stars  have  arisen  by  the 
process  of  capture  in  the  course  of  millions  of  ages.  It  will  be  the 
main  purpose  of  this  article  to  discuss  the  results  arrived  at  in  this 
general  investigation  of  the  origin  of  star  clusters;  but  before  tak- 
ing up  this  subject  in  detail  it  will  be  allowable  to  treat  briefly  of  the 
conclusions  reached  by  the  illustrious  Poincare  in  his  Leqons  sur  les 
Hypotheses  Cosmo goniques,  1911,  and  to  notice  also  the  unimportant 
objections  advanced  by  Prof.  Charles  Andre  in  Scientia,  No.  2,  1912. 

The  Views  of  Poincare. 

In  his  Legons  sur  les  Hypotheses  Cosmo  goniques,  1911,  M. 
Poincare  gives  a  summary  of  the  various  theories  of  cosmogony, 
and  in  two  chapters  discusses  results  arrived  at  in  my  Researches 
on  the  Evolution  of  the  Stellar  Systems,  Vol.  II,  1910.*  He  exam- 

*  These  chapters  appeared  in  translation  in  The  Monist  of  July,  1912. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

ines  and  adopts  the  proof  therein  given  that  the  roundness  of  the 
orbits  of  the  planets  and  satellites  is  due  to  the  secular  effects  of 
the  action  of  a  resisting  medium.  He  concurs  in  the  capture  of 
satellites,  as  well  as  in  the  new  theory  of  spiral  and  ring  nebulae. 
M.  Poincare  especially  remarks  how  well  the  resisting  medium  ex- 
plains the  roundness  of  the  orbits  of  the  planets  and  satellites ;  and 
altogether  is  favorable  to  the  recent  development  of  cosmogony  into 
a  new  science  of  the  starry  heavens. 

One  point  in  my  work,  however,  has  been  slightly  misunderstood 
by  Poincare,  and  I  will  therefore  dwell  upon  it  here.  After  out- 
lining the  leading  principles  of  the  Capture  Theory  he  adds  that 
while  it  fully  explains  the  roundness  of  the  orbits,  it  does  not  give 
a  satisfactory  explanation  of  the  inclinations  of  the  planetary  orbits. 
But  here  he  has  evidently  lost  sight  of  the  nature  of  the  spiral  nebula 
from  which  our  solar  system  is  supposed  to  have  arisen. 

The  Capture  Theory  means  primarily  that  all  revolving  bodies 
are  added  on  from  without, — the  planets  being  added  to  the  sun 
and  the  satellites  added  to  the  several  planets ;  but  it  is  not  held  that 
the  entrance  into  our  system  was  from  all  directions  over  the  celes- 
tial sphere  and  thus  entirely  at  random.  On  the  contrary  it  is  care- 
fully explained  in  my  work  that  the  system  from  the  beginning  had 
a  fundamental  plane  of  maximum  areas,  due  to  the  fact  that  a  spiral 
nebula  is  formed  by  two  principal  streams  coiling  about  one  another ; 
and  the  plane  of  maximum  areas  is  the  plane  determined  by  these 
predominant  streams. 

In  the  condensation  of  a  nebula  an  infinite  number  of  minor 
streams  probably  are  involved ;  but  the  whirling  motion  is  made 
possible  only  by  two  predominant  streams,  as  shown  in  photographs 
of  spiral  nebulae.  That  is  to  say,  there  is  more  matter  in  the  two 
large  streams  than  in  the  smaller  ones ;  and  this  gives  a  fundamental 
plane  to  the  system  when  it  becomes  mature,  just  like  that  in  which 
the  planets  of  the  solar  system  are  found  to  move.  The  planetary 
orbits  ought  not  to  lie  exactly  in  the  same  plane,  but  near  an  in- 
variable plane,  such  as  Laplace  in  1784  proved  to  exist  in  every 
system  of  bodies  subjected  to  the  mutual  gravitation  of  its  parts. 

The  comets  or  smaller  masses  of  nebulosity  naturally  should 
be  inclined  at  all  angles  to  the  invariable  plane ;  but  as  they  intersect 
that  plane  twice  in  their  orbital  motion  about  the  sun,  they  will  sooner 
or  later  pass  near  a  planet  revolving  in  an  orbit  lying  near  the  fun- 
damental plane  of  the  system,  and  their  orbits  are  thus  subjected  to 
profound  changes  of  position  as  well  as  of  form  and  extent.  Count- 


62O  THE  MONIST. 

less  comets  are  destroyed  in  building  up  the  planets;  so  that  much 
matter  not  originally  lying  in  the  plane  of  the  planets  is  finally  cap- 
tured and  drawn  into  that  plane,  as  the  masses  of  the  planets  grad- 
ually augment,  and  they  are  drawn  nearer  the  sun  in  orbits  becom- 
ing ever  smaller  and  smaller,  and  rounder  and  rounder. 

Thus  on  the  one  hand  the  resistance  of  cometary  matter  reduces 
the.  size  of  the  planetary  orbits  and  makes  them  rounder,  while  on 
the  other  hand  the  growth  of  these  masses  increases  their  mutual 
attraction;  and  if  they  were  originally  near  the  plane  of  the  pre- 
dominant streams,  in  time  they  come  to  move  almost  exactly  in  one 
plane,  as  now  observed  in  our  actual  planetary  system. 

For  as  our  system  has  shrunk,  and  the  original  orbits  were 
hundreds  of  times  larger  than  at  present,  the  nuclei  at  the  outset 
were  not  necessarily  very  near  the  plane  in  which  they  now  move, 
but  may  have  departed  from  it  considerably.  Mutual  inclinations 
of  a  few  degrees  now  found  in  our  system  are  magnified  at  hundred- 
fold primordial  distances  into  very  great  absolute  distances;  so  that 
the  original  streams  need  not  have  been  at  all  compressed,  but  may 
have  been  exceedingly  diffuse,  just  as  actual  nebulae  appear  to  be. 

Accordingly  it  is  a  remarkable  fact  that  the  theory  which  ac- 
counts for  the  roundness  of  the  orbits  of  the  planets  also  explains 
the  small  mutual  inclinations  of  their  orbits,  and  the  rotation  of  the 
sun  about  an  axis  nearly  perpendicular  to  the  plane  in  which  the 
planets  revolve.  The  explanation  of  the  origin  of  our  system  from 
a  spiral  nebula  thus  appears  to  be  entirely  satisfactory. 

The  Views  and  Objections  of  Andre. 

The  objections  to  the  Capture  Theory  advanced  by  Andre  are 
easily  shown  to  be  without  the  slightest  foundation.  It  is  quite 
unnecessary  to  consider  most  of  them,  and  I  will  therefore  content 
myself  with  the  three  chief  ones,  which  will  sufficiently  show  the 
weakness  of  the  rest. 

1.  Andre  claims  that  the  spherical  expansion  in  Babinet's  cri- 
terion as  I  have  used  it  is  not  strictly  in  accordance  with  Laplace's 
theory,  because  Laplace  did  not  imagine  the  sun's  atmosphere  to  be 
expanded  in  a  spherical  form,  but  rather  in  the  form  of  a  flat  disc. 
This  objection  is  quite  devoid  of  foundation,  as  will  appear  from  the 
following  simple  considerations. 

a.  If  the  expansion  be  spheroidal,  as  a  flat  disc,  more  of  the 
matter  is  at  greater  distance  from  the  center,  for  given  volume, 
than  in  a  spherical  expansion;  so  that  the  moment  of  inertia  is  in- 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  621 

creased,  and  with  constant  moment  of  momentum  the  angular  veloc- 
ity is  therefore  decreased.  Hence  a  discoidal  expansion  of  the  sun 
is  more  unfavorable  to  Laplace's  hypothesis  than  the  spherical  ex- 
pansion used  by  me.  For  in  case  of  a  sphere  the  moment  of  inertia 
is  shown  in  works  on  the  calculus  to  be  2/5 (Mr2),  where  r  is  the 
radius  and  M  the  mass ;  in  an  ellipsoid  with  equatorial  axes  a  and  b 
it  is  M/5(a2  +  b2),  and  when  a-b}  as  in  an  ellipsoid  of  revolution, 
this  becomes  2/5 (Ma2),  a  being  the  equatorial  axis. 

b.  To  reduce  this  to  numbers  I  took  ellipsoids  with  meridian 
sections  of  eccentricity  0.10,  0.25,  0.5,  and  0.8,  giving  oblatenesses 
of  0.00501,  0.03176,  0.13397,  and  0.40000  respectively;  and  found 
a2  =  1 .00336r2  ;  a2  =  1 .0217r2 ;  a2  =  1 . 1525r2  ;  a2  =  1 .4057r2.  This 
shows  how  the  moment  of  inertia  increases  as  the  oblateness  in- 
creases, and  thus  proves  a  corresponding  decrease  of  the  angular 
velocity  of  rotation  below  that  published  in  my  tables  of  Babinet's 
criterion.  The  objection  of  Andre  therefore  has  not  the  slightest 
foundation,  because  my  calculations  are  more  favorable  to  Laplace's 
theory  than  those  based  on  the  theory  of  an  oblate  spheroid. 

2.  Andre  dwells  on  the  fact  that  Laplace  imagined  only  the 
atmosphere  of  the  sun  expanded  to  the  orbits  of  the  planets.     But 
as  the  sun  itself  when  so  expanded  becomes  much  rarer  than  most 
atmospheres  we  are  familiar  with,  it  is  readily  seen  that  this  point 
is  not  well  taken.     When  the  sun  is  expanded  to  Neptune's  orbit, 
the  average  density  of  the  nebula  is  260  million  times  less  than  that 
of  air  at  sea  level.    Nothing  more  need  be  said  on  this  point.    Such 
a  medium  could  exert  little  or  no  hydrostatic  pressure  from  the 
center,  and  Laplace's  theory  of  the  detachment  of  zones  of  vapor 
under  conditions  of  hydrostatic  pressure  implies  that  he  overlooked 
the  rarity  of  this  medium,  which  makes  such  a  thing  as  hydrostatic 
pressure  quite  impossible.     No  alteration  of  central  arrangement 
of  density  would  materially  change  this  result,  and  we  may  thus 
dismiss  it  without  further  comment. 

3.  As  the  centrifugal  force,  by  Babinet's  criterion,  is  only  a  ten 
millionth  part  of  that  required  to  detach  the  earth,  and  a  three  hun- 
dred millionth  of  that  required  to  detach  Neptune,  while  the  hydro- 
static pressure  likewise  is  insensible,  it  is  clear  that  no  such  detach- 
ment as  Laplace  imagined  ever  took  place.     Andre,  Ligondes  and 
other  French  writers  are  simply  injuring  the  memory  of  Laplace 
by  presenting  to  the  Paris  Academy  of  Sciences  conclusions  which 
would  be  immediately  rejected  by  Laplace  himself  if  he  were  living 
to-day. 


622  THE  MONIST. 

After  having  studied  the  works  of  this  great  master  of  celestial 
mechanics  from  the  days  of  my  youth,  I  believe  I  have  followed 
his  spirit  in  rejecting  what  is  now  known  to  be  false.  Professor 
Andre  is  in  the  unfortunate  position  of  having  written  books  favor- 
able to  the  abandoned  theory  of  Laplace ;  but  he  should  aim  at  truth 
rather  than  perpetual  consistency,  and  modify  his  views  to  meet  the 
latest  discoveries  in  science.  For  a  true  philosopher  does  not  aim 
at  supporting  his  earlier  writings,  but  at  gradually  attaining  the 
truth,  even  if  his  first  work  has  to  be  modified  or  entirely  abandoned. 
The  successors  of  Laplace  obviously  should  act  upon  this  laudable 
principle. 

4.  Even  if  the  retrograde  satellites  and  a  multitude  of  other 
phenomena  did  not  tell  us  unmistakably  that  all  the  satellites  have 
been  captured,  and  we  still  tried  to  explain  these  bodies  by  the  de- 
tachment theory  of  Laplace,  we  should  remain  quite  in  the  dark  as 
to  the  origin  of  the  observed  rotations.  They  would  be  simply 
assumed,  and  not  explained ;  and  so  we  should  have  no  rational 
theory  of  the  formation  of  the  solar  system;  whereas  the  Capture 
Theory  gives  a  simple  and  natural  explanation  of  the  rotations  and 
obliquities  as  well  as  the  orbital  motion  of  the  satellites,  and  the 
variations  of  their  brightness,  the  lunar  craters  and  maria  and  kin- 
dred phenomena ;  and  all  the  phenomena  are  so  woven  together  that 
it  is  impossible  to  doubt  the  truth  of  the  new  theory. 

In  the  same  way,  even  if  the  solar  nebula  could  have  rotated 
rapidly  enough  to  detach  zones  of  vapor  as  Laplace  imagined,  it 
would  still  be  impossible  to  account  for  so  rapid  a  rotation.  For- 
tunately Babinet's  criterion  shows  that  no  such  rapid  rotation  for  the 
detachment  of  zones  of  vapor  ever  took  place ;  and  that  Laplace  was 
deceived  by  the  roundness  of  the  planetary  orbits,  which  we  now 
recognize  to  be  due  to  the  secular  action  of  the  nebular  resisting 
medium  formerly  pervading  our  solar  system. 

Necessity  for  Wider  View  of  all  Sidereal  Systems. 

It  requires  no  elaborate  argument  to  convince  any  philosophic 
investigator  that  the  laws  of  cosmical  evolution  can  best  be  deduced 
from  the  study  of  nature  in  the  widest  sense.  The  narrowness  of 
the  cosmogony  of  Laplace  arose  from  the  fact  that  it  was  based 
wholly  on  our  solar  system,  and  that  too  before  the  system  was 
fully  understood.  The  roundness  of  the  orbits  of  the  planets  and 
satellites  and  the  survival  of  a  ring  about  Saturn  led  to  the  idea 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  623 

that  all  these  bodies  had  originated  by  the  detachment  of  rings. 
Yet  as  soon  as  the  orbits  of  the  double  stars  were  determined,  they 
were  found  to  have  eccentricities  of  every  degree,  between  the  round 
orbits  characteristic  of  the  planets  and  satellites  and  the  very  elon- 
gated orbits  characteristic  of  the  comets.  The  development  of  double 
stars  obviously  could  not  have  been  by  the  formation  of  rings  as  im- 
agined by  Laplace. 

Accordingly  without  such  a  comprehensive  view  of  the  different 
types  of  systems  it  would  be  vain  to  hope  for  the  deduction  of  a 
general  law  of  nature.  The  folly  of  adhering  to  the  old  methods 
of  Laplace  based  on  an  imperfect  knowledge  of  the  solar  system 
alone  is  thus  apparent ;  and  after  what  is  now  shown,  from  Babinet's 
criterion,  as  to  the  impossibility  of  detaching  masses  or  rings,  there 
is  no  course  open  to  us  but  to  reject  Laplace's  hypothesis  once  for 
all.  It  does  not  give  us  a  general  law  of  nature,  and  is  not  true 
even  for  the  special  case  of  the  solar  system. 

Our  hope  for  finding  the  law  of  nature  must  be  based  on  the 
study  of  double  and  multiple  stars,  and  sidereal  systems  of  higher 
order.  Now  it  happens  that  of  the  various  sidereal  systems  known 
to  the  astronomer,  the  globular  clusters  are  the  most  complex,  and 
at  the  same  time  the  most  symmetrical  and  regular  in  their  consti- 
tution. If  therefore  any  light  can  be  obtained  on  the  formation  of 
sidereal  systems  of  such  high  order,  it  might  be  possible  to  derive 
principles  which  could  be  applied  to  less  symmetrical  systems  of 
lower  order.  This  is  what  I  have  done  in  my  recent  investigation  of 
the  origin  of  clusters.  Having  deduced  the  law  of  nature  from  the 
highest  and  most  complex  systems,  with  wonderful  regularity  of 
figure,  I  have  proceeded  to  apply  it  also  to  systems  of  the  lowest 
type,  as  the  solar  system  and  the  double  and  multiple  stars.  This 
new  method  of  procedure  is  so  important,  that  it  becomes  advisable 
to  explain  it  in  some  detail. 

Nature  of  Clusters,  Average  Distance  of  the  Stars  Apart,  Increase 
of  Density  Towards  Center. 

Sir  William  Herschel  always  considered  the  globular  clusters 
to  be  the  most  wonderful  of  all  sidereal  systems.  He  never  ceased 
to  marvel  at  the  existence  of  these  swarms  of  stars,  which  were 
known  to  be  aggregations  of  suns;  and  he  inferred  that  at  length 
they  had  been  moulded  into  the  spherical  form  by  the  action  of  cen- 
tral powers. 


624  THE  MONIST. 

Even  in  the  time  of  Herschel  it  was  recognized  that  the  clusters 
are  very  far  from  the  earth,  and  thus  that  the  component  stars  are 
not  really  close  together,  but  separated  by  intervals  which  are  very 
great  compared  to  those  which  separate  the  planets  from  the  sun. 

More  modern  discovery  has  confirmed  the  sagacious  conjectures 
of  the  great  Herschel.  The  latest  investigation  of  the  profundity 
of  the  Milky  Way,  which  I  finished  in  November,  1911,  and  have 
just  published  in  the  Proceedings  of  the  American  Philosophical 
Society  at  Philadelphia,  shows  that  the  remotest  clusters  are  re- 
moved from  us  by  at  least  a  million  light-years.  Indeed  this  deter- 
mination of  the  depth  of  the  Milky  Way  shows  that  the  remotest 
stars  may  be  removed  from  us  by  distances  of  five  or  ten  million 
light-years;  but  even  with  most  of  the  clusters  at  distances  of  hun- 
dreds of  thousands  of  light-years,  it  is  possible  to  say  with  certainty 
that  the  average  space  between  the  stars  in  globular  clusters  is  of 
the  order  of  a  light-year,  which  is  63275  times  the  distance  of  the 
earth  from  the  sun.  We  thus  have  the  spectacle  of  systems  of  stars 
separated  by  great  intervals,  but  so  remote  as  to  be  drawn  together 
by  perspective  into  a  small  angular  space  on  the  surface  of  the  sky. 

The  density  in  these  masses  of  stars  was  found  by  Herschel 
to  be  always  greatest  towards  the  center;  and  in  fact  to  be  in 
excess  of  that  corresponding  to  the  supposition  of  equal  scattering. 
Herschel  therefore  inferred  that  the  accumulation  in  the  centers 
of  the  clusters  must  be  due  to  the  secular  action  of  a  clustering 
power,  which  he  believed  to  be  nothing  else  than  universal  gravi- 
tation working  over  millions  of  ages.  He  remarked  that  the  Milky 
Way  presented  the  aspect  of  a  clustering  stream  traversing  the 
heavens  as  an  irregular  band  of  milky  light;  and  as  he  had  found 
the  sidereal  universe  to  be  greatly  extended  in  the  direction  of  the 
plane  of  the  Milky  Way,  he  correctly  inferred  that  the  clustering 
stream  thus  presented  to  the  eye  was  the  effect  of  distance  and  of 
local  aggregations  of  the  stars  into  star-clouds  and  clusters.  The 
stars  are  spread  out  into  a  comparatively  thin  stratum,  and  at  great 
distance  the  effect  is  to  give  the  appearance  of  the  Milky  Way, 
which  thus  appears  as  a  clustering  stream  several  degrees  in  width. 

How  the  Stars  are  Captured  in  Clusters. 

In  the  memoir  above  referred  to  I  have  established  the  capture 
of  stars  by  a  cluster,  and  the  secular  shrinkage  of  the  cluster,  by 
the  use  of  Green's  theorem  for  the  transformation  of  a  triple  in- 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  625 

tegral  appropriate  for  space  into  a  double  integral  over  the  surface 
of  the  cluster.  By  showing  that  the  surface  shrinks  as  the  result 
of  close  appulses  among  the  stars,  and  also  as  the  outcome  of  mutual 
gravitation,  even  when  no  close  approach  occurs,  it  is  found  that 
the  cluster  becomes  more  and  more  compressed,  with  density  ac- 
cumulating towards  the  center. 

The  attraction  of  members  of  a  cluster  is  analogous  to  surface 
tension  in  working  to  decrease  the  volume  of  a  bubble,  or  in  round- 
ing up  a  drop  of  dew,  to  give  minimal  surface  for  a  given  volume. 
In  the  same  way  gravity  tends  to  make  a  planet  perfectly  round, 
except  as  modified  by  rotation  into  an  oblate  figure.  Herschel  used 
such  analogies  in  his  argument  for  a  clustering  power,  which  he 
inferred  to  be  moulding  the  figures  of  clusters.  And  recently  I  have 
tested  his  suggestion  mathematically,  and  found  a  conclusive  proof 
that  the  argument  is  correct. 

To  give  a  simple  analogy  for  the  capture  of  stars  in  clusters, 
with  known  processes  in  the  solar  system,  we  may  remark  that 
Jupiter  captures  the  comets  crossing  over  his  orbit,  and  transforms 
their  paths  till  they  lie  wholly  within  that  of  the  planet.  In  this 
way  he  has  captured  quite  a  family  of  comets  and  thrown  their  or- 
bits within  his  own  orbit.  Now  in  the  memoir  above  referred  to 
I  have  shown  that  a  shell  of  stars  in  a  cluster  acts  very  much  as 
Jupiter  does  on  the  comets — and  thus  tends  to  reduce  the  path  of  an 
oscillating  star  till  it  comes  within  the  confines  of  the  shell. 

Accordingly  if  a  star  from  without  once  enters  a  cluster,  and 
thus  begins  to  traverse  the  series  of  shells  of  which  the  cluster 
is  made  up,  it  will  never  quit  the  swarm  but  be  gradually  drawn  in, 
and  captured,  during  one  or  more  complete  oscillations.  The  ex- 
tent of  its  outward  journey  from  the  cluster,  if  any  occurs,  will  be 
decreased,  until  finally  it  is  dragged  down  to  the  level  of  the  shell, 
and  becomes  a  member  of  the  cluster.  This  is  one  of  the  most  re- 
markable results  of  our  dynamical  theory  of  clusters.  The  Cap- 
ture Theory  being  thus  verified  for  these  globular  masses  of  stars, 
it  naturally  may  be  expected  to  operate  in  systems  of  lower  order. 

No  Possible  Origin  of  Clusters  Except  that  Outlined  by  the  Capture 

Theory. 

The  globular  clusters  are  so  perfectly  symmetrical  that  they 
become  of  high  interest  in  elucidating  the  problems  of  cosmogony. 
For  it  is  not  conceivable  that  systems  of  such  large  mass,  great 


626  THE  MONIST. 

extent  and  perfect  symmetry,  can  have  arisen,  except  by  the  gather- 
ing together  of  stars  from  a  wider  extent  of  space. 

No  process  of  collision,  for  example,  would  account  for  the 
globular  clusters;  for  by  impact  the  matter  of  two  hypothetically 
disrupted  masses  would  neither  be  symmetrically  distributed  nor 
dispersed  over  such  a  vast  space  as  that  now  occupied  by  the  thou- 
sands of  suns  composing  a  cluster.  Then,  again,  to  be  effective 
such  hypothetical  collision  would  have  to  be  between  approximately 
equal  giant  suns;  and  there  are  too  few  stars  of  such  enormous 
mass  for  pairs  of  them  ever  to  come  into  bodily  collision. 

Accordingly,  a  little  consideration  shows  us,  on  the  one  hand, 
that  such  giant  collisions  would  not  occur;  and,  on  the  other,  that 
even  if  they  could  take  place  such  widely  diffused  and  symmetrical 
swarms  of  stars  could  not  arise  by  this  process.  The  globular 
clusters  therefore  are  due  to  the  aggregation  of  stars  once  symmetri- 
cally and  widely  distributed  in  space.  This  gives  us  a  good  illus- 
tration of  the  Capture  Theory  on  the  most  stupendous  scale.  Simi- 
lar views  were  reached  by  Herschel,  without  mathematical  investi- 
gation of  the  subject,  such  as  I  have  recently  developed;  and  it 
may  be  remarked  that  he  found  the  evidence  of  a  clustering  power 
most  convincing. 

The  New  General  Catalogue  of  Nebulae  and  Clusters,  published 
by  the  Royal  Astronomical  Society  of  London  in  1888,  contains  a 
list  of  more  than  one  hundred  globular  clusters,  mostly  distributed 
along  the  course  of  the  Milky  Way.  The  clustering  of  the  stars 
into  great  systems  about  so  many  centers  shows  how  general  and 
widespread  this  tendency  is  in  nature. 

If  now  we  recall  that  only  the  oldest  sidereal  systems  can  have 
attained  a  state  of  perfect  symmetry,  it  is  obvious  that  a  larger 
number  of  sidereal  systems  might  be  expected  to  have  an  irregular 
and  unsymmetrical  aspect.  The  globular  clusters  are  therefore  only 
a  part  of  the  aggregations  of  stars  exhibiting  the  effect  of  the 
clustering  power;  but  the  perfection  of  this  type  of  system  renders 
it  eminently  adapted  to  disclosing  the  process  by  which  all  clusters 
are  formed.  For  if  the  law  of  nature  can  be  deduced  from  the 
perfect  type  of  sidereal  development,  it  may  with  equal  certainty 
be  inferred  to  operate  in  those  sidereal  systems  which  have  not  yet 
attained  to  full  maturity.  By  investigating  the  different  types  of 
sidereal  systems  our  studies  may  thus  disclose  the  general  law  of 
cosmical  evolution  and  embrace  phenomena  extending  over  millions 
of  ages! 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  627 

The  Law  of  Nature  Embraces  also  Systems  of  Lower  Order,  and 

Therefore  the  Planetary  System  and  the  Systems 

of  Double   and  Multiple  Stars. 

Those  who  believe  in  the  uniformity  and  continuity  of  the  laws 
of  nature,  as  laid  down  by  Newton  in  the  Principia,  1687,  will 
quickly  realize  that  the  law  of  cosmical  evolution  established  for 
the  globular  clusters  should  necessarily  hold  also  for  systems  of 
lower  order.  Rule  I:  "We  are  to  admit  no  more  causes  of  natural 
things  than  such  as  are  both  true  and  sufficient  to  explain  their 
appearances."  Rule  II:  "Therefore  to  the  same  natural  effects  we 
must,  as  far  as  possible,  assign  the  same  causes." 

Accordingly,  in  line  with  these  rules  of  Newton,  I  have  shown 
that  the  Capture  Theory  will  explain  the  formation  of  the  solar 
system,  as  well  as  the  double  and  multiple  stars:  and  having  found 
the  principle  to  be  the  same  throughout  the  sidereal  universe,  I  have 
inferred  that  nature's  law  everywhere  is  one  of  adding  on  from 
without.  The  component  stars  are  added  to  the  clusters,  and  drawn 
nearer  and  nearer  the  center;  the  planets  added  to  the  sun  and 
made  to  revolve  in  smaller  and  smaller  and  rounder  and  rounder 
orbits.  Likewise  the  satellites  were  added  on  to  their  several  plan- 
ets, and  the  moon  captured  by  the  earth.  The  double  and  multiple 
stars  were  formed  on  the  same  principle — the  nuclei  having  origi- 
nated in  the  distance,  and  subsequently  approached  the  centers  about 
which  they  now  revolve.  This  gives  us  a  general  law  of  nature  of 
the  utmost  simplicity. 

And  not  only  is  the  generality  of  the  law  proved  by  force  of 
analogy,  but  also  by  direct  mathematical  demonstrations  in  the  solar 
system,  deduced  from  Babinet's  Criterion;  while  in  the  clusters  the 
proof  is  so  obvious  that  it  need  scarcely  be  emphasized.  The  demon- 
stration of  this  law  in  the  double  and  multiple  stars  is  similar  to 
that  available  in  the  solar  system;  and  moreover  is  supported  by 
the  analogy  of  the  clusters,  into  which  the  multiple  stars  merge 
by  insensible  degrees,  when  the  number  of  bodies  in  a  group  is  in- 
creased indefinitely. 

Accordingly  nothing  is  more  certain  than  that  the  law  of  cos- 
mical evolution  now  recognized  is  the  true  law  of  nature.  It  does 
not  even  resemble  the  abandoned  theory  of  Laplace,  but  has  con- 
siderable resemblance  to  the  general  outline  of  the  nebular  hypoth- 
esis as  traced  by  Sir  William  Herschel.  In  particular  Herschel's 
theory  of  clusters,  as  originating  by  the  aggregation  of  isolated 


628  THE  MONIST. 

stars  is  deserving  of  attention;  for  this  is  the  earliest  outline  of  a 
process  of  capture  similar  to  that  now  worked  out  in  detail  and 
shown  to  be  applicable  to  all  types  of  systems  observed  in  the  sidereal 
universe. 

In  conclusion  it  seems  advisable  to  close  this  discussion  by  the 
following  summary  quoted  from  my  latest  memoir  on  The  Dynam- 
ical Theory  of  Clusters. 

Summary  and  Conclusions. 

Without  attempting,  in  this  closing  section,  to  recapitulate  the 
contents  of  this  memoir  in  detail,  it  may  yet  be  well  to  draw  atten- 
tion to  some  of  the  most  significant  conclusions  at  which  we  have 
arrived. 

1.  As  intimated  in  the  first  section  of  this  paper  the  problem  of 
w-bodies,  under  ideal  dynamical  conditions,  remains  forever  beyond 
the  power  of  the  most  general  methods  of  analysis ;  but  the  dynam- 
ical theory  of  clusters  gives  us  the  one  secular  solution  of  this  prob- 
lem found  under  actual  conditions  in  nature.    For  when  n  is  of  the 
order  of  1000,  so  as  to  give  rise  to  a  cluster,  the  clustering  power 
observed  by  Herschel  operates  to  exhaust  the  mutual  potential  en- 
ergy of  the  system,  and  bring  about  increasing  accumulation  in  the 
center,  so  that  the  cluster  finally  unites  into  a  single  mass  of  enor- 
mous magnitude.    Probably  the  giant  stars  of  the  type  of  Canopus 
and  Arcturus  have  arisen  in  this  way. 

2.  And  since  attendant  bodies  of  every  class — as  satellites,  plan- 
ets, comets,  double  and  multiple  stars — tend  everywhere  to  approach 
the  centers  about  which  they  revolve,  as  an  inevitable  effect  of  the 
growth  of  the  central  masses  and  of  the  action  of  the  resisting 
medium  over  long  ages,  it  follows  that  the  secular  solution  of  the 
problem  of  clusters  is  more  or  less  valid  for  all  cosmical  systems. 
They  finally  end  by  the  absorption  of  the  attendant  bodies  in  the 
central  masses  which  now  govern  their  motions. 

3.  The  dynamical  theory  of  globular  clusters  shows  that  the 
clustering  power  inferred  by  Herschel  is  nothing  else  than  the  action 
of  universal  gravitation ;  and  that  it  operates  on  all  sidereal  systems, 
but  does  not  produce  the  cumulative  effect  which  Herschel  ascribed 
to  the  ravages  of  time  inside  of  millions  of  ages. 

4.  The  globular  clusters  are  formed  by  the  gathering  together 
of  stars  and  elements  of  nebulosity  from  all  directions  in  space ;  and 
this  points  to  the  expulsion  of  dust  from  the  stars  of  the  Milky  Way, 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  629 

and  its  collection  about  the  region  of  the  formation  in  such  manner 
as  to  give  essential  symmetry  in  the  final  arrangement  of  the  cluster, 
which  doubtless  has  some  motion  of  rotation,  and  originally  a  ten- 
dency to  spiral  movement. 

5.  The  stars  and  smaller  masses  are  captured  by  the  mutual  action 
of  the  other  members  of  the  cluster,  and  worked  down  towards  the 
center  of  the  mass.    This  gives  a  central  density  in  excess  of  that 
appropriate  to  a  sphere  of  monatomic  gas  in  convective  equilibrium 
(A.  N.  4053  and  A.  N.  4104). 

6.  The  density  of  the  clusters  is  greater  on  the  outer  border 
than  in  a  globe  of  monatomic  gases,  which  shows  that  stars  are  still 
collecting  from  the  surrounding  regions  of  space.     The  starless 
aspect  of  the  remoter  regions  about  clusters  is  an  effect  of  the  rav- 
ages of  time,  as  correctly  inferred  by  Herschel  in  the  course  of  his 
penetrating  sweeps  of  the  starry  heavens. 

7.  And  just  as  clusters  under  the  mutual  gravitation  of  the  com- 
ponent stars  contract  their  dimensions,  with  time,  chiefly  owing  to 
the  growth  of  the  central  masses,  so  also  do  other  systems,  whether 
the  mass-distribution  be  single,  giving  a  system  made  up  of  a  sun 
and  planets,  or  double,  triple  and  multiple,  giving  binary,  triple  or 
multiple  stars,  or  sidereal  systems  of  still  higher  order.     The  ten- 
dency everywhere  is  from  a  wider  to  a  narrower  distribution  of  the 
large  bodies ;  while  the  only  throwing  off  that  ever  occurs  is  of  par- 
ticles driven  away  from  the  stars  by  the  action  of  repulsive  forces. 

8.  The  orbits  of  the  stellar  and  planetary  systems  are  decreased 
by  the  growth  of  the  central  masses  and  rounded  up  by  the  action  of 
the  nebular  resisting  medium.    And  in  like  manner  all  clusters  tend 
to  assume  spherical  or  globular  figures,  so  as  to  justify  the  expression 
of  Plato,  that  the  Deity  always  geometrizes;  or  Newton's  remark 
that  the  agency  operating  in  the  construction  of  the  solar  system  was 
"very  well  skilled  in  mechanics  and  geometry." 

9.  Newton  required  the  intervention  of  the  Deity  to  give  the 
planets  revolving  motion  in  their  orbits,  because  in  the  absence  of 
repulsive  forces  he  could  not  account  for  the  dispersion  of  the  matter 
so  as  to  produce  the  tangential  motions  actually  observed.    By  means 
of  the  theory  of  repulsive  forces,  however,  it  is  now  possible  to 
explain  these  projectile  motions,  which  Herschel  likewise  pointed  to 
as  the  chief  agency  for  the  preservation  of  sidereal  systems.    The 
only  assumption  necessary  is  an  unsymmetrical  figure  of  the  primor- 
dial nebula,  giving  a  whirling  motion  about  the  center  as  the  system 
develops ;  and  since  the  dust  gathers  from  all  directions  it  is  certain 


630  THE  MONIST. 

that  this  lack  of  perfect  symmetry  will  always  develop,  as  we  see 
also  by  the  spiral  nebulae. 

10.  It  is  this  unsymmetrical  form  of  the  spiral  nebulae  produced 
by  the  gathering  of  the  dust  from  the  stars,  or  the  slight  relative 
tangential  motion  of  stars  formed  separately  but  finally  made  to 
revolve  together  as  a  binary  system,  that  gives  the  projectile  forces 
with  which  they  are  set  revolving  in  their  orbits.    In  no  case  have 
they  resulted  from  the  rupture  of  a  rotating  mass  of  fluid  under 
conditions  of  hydrostatic  pressure  as  formerly  believed  by  Darwin, 
Poincare  and  See. 

11.  Even  if  the  rotation  could  become  rapid  enough  to  produce 
a  separation,  under  conditions  of  hydrostatic  pressure,  by  rupture 
of  a  figure  of  equilibrium,  there  would  still  be  the  equal  or  greater 
difficulty  of  explaining  the  origin  of  the  primitive  rapid  rotation. 
This  last  difficulty  escaped  notice  till  we  came  to  assign  the  cause 
of  rotations,  and  found  that  mechanical  throwing  off  was  impossible 
under  actual  conditions  in  nature.    It  is  therefore  recognized,  from 
the  definite  proof  furnished  by  Babinet's  criterion  in  the  solar  sys- 
tem, that  such  a  thing  as  a  throwing  off  never  takes  place ;  but  that  all 
planetary  and  stellar  bodies  are  formed  in  the  distance,  and  after- 
wards near  the  centers  about  which  they  subsequently  revolve. 

12.  This  gives  us  a  fundamental  law  of  the  firmament — the 
planets  being  added  on  to  the  sun,  the  satellites  added  on  to  their  plan- 
ets, the  moon  added  on  to  the  earth,  and  the  companions  added  on  to 
the  double  and  multiple  stars — which  now  is  found  to  be  beautifully 
confirmed  by  the  dynamical  theory  of  the  globular  clusters.     It  is 
not  often  that  such  a  great  law  of  nature  can  be  brought  to  light,  and 
it  is  worthy  of  the  more  consideration  from  the  circumstance  that  it 
explains  all  classes  of  stellar  systems  by  a  single  general  principle. 

13.  As  sidereal  systems  of  lower  order  are  conserved  by  projec- 
tile forces,  it  is  probable  that  the  clusters  likewise  have  a  spiral 
motion  of  rotation,  with  similar  projectile  forces  tending  to  counter- 
act simple  progressive  collapse.    The  period  of  the  orbital  revolution 
of  the  stars  of  a  cluster  is  found  to  be  common  to  all,  without  regard 
to  the  dimensions  of  the  elliptical  orbits  described;  and  thus  the 
whole  system  may  have  a  common  period  of  oscillation,  after  which 
the  initial  condition  is  perfectly  restored.     This  possibility  in  the 
dynamics  of  a  cluster  is  exceedingly  wonderful  and  results  from  the 
central  attraction  depending  directly  on  the  distance. 

14.  The  equality  of  brightness  in  star  clusters  shows  that  some 
process  of  compensation  between  the  attractive  and  repulsive  forces 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  63! 

has  produced  stars  of  wonderful  uniformity  of  luster.  Thus  the 
present  investigation  confirms  the  previous  researches  on  the  evolu- 
tion of  the  stellar  systems,  which  have  laid  the  foundations  for  a  New 
Science  of  the  Starry  Heavens. 

15.  Accordingly  the  Capture  Theory  of  cosmical  evolution  being 
now  firmly  established  for  the  clusters,  where  the  nature  of  the 
process  is  entirely  clear,  it  becomes  at  once  a  guide  to  us  in  dealing 
with  systems  of  lower  order;  and  we  see  that  the  law  of  nature  is 
uniform  and  everywhere  the  same,  the  large  bodies  working  in 
towards  the  centers  of  attraction,  while  the  only  throwing  off  that 
ever  takes  place  is  of  small  particles  driven  out  of  the  stars  by  the 
action  of  repulsive  forces.    All  planetary  bodies  are  formed  in  the 
distance,  and  have  their  orbits  reduced  in  size  by  increase  of  the 
central  masses,  and  rounded  up  by  moving  in  a  resisting  medium. 
This  is  a  perfectly  general  law  of  the  sidereal  universe.    It  verifies 
the  early  conjectures  of  Plato  and  Newton  concerning  the  stability 
of  the  order  of  the  world  and  shows  that  these  illustrious  philosophers 
were  quite  justified  in  concluding  that  the  Deity  always  geometrizes. 
The  spiral  nebulae  tend  to  develop  systems  with  rounder  and  rounder 
orbits,  and  the  clusters  made  up  of  thousands  of  stars  assume  globu- 
lar figures  with  minimal  surfaces  and  internal  density  so  arranged 
as  to  give  maximum  exhaustion  of  the  potential  energy. 

16.  This  is  geometry  of  the  most  marvelous  kind,  as  we  find  it 
impressed  on  the  systems  of  the  sidereal  universe ;  and  the  perfection 
of  this  most  beautiful  science  of  celestial  geometry  may  be  considered 
the  ultimate  object  of  the  labors  of  the  astronomer.     The  philo- 
sophic observer  is  not  and  never  can  be  content  with  mere  observa- 
tions of  details  which  do  not  disclose  the  living,  all-pervading  spirit 
of  nature. 

17.  If,  then,  the  mystery  of  the  gathering  of  stars  into  clusters 
is  now  penetrated  and  traced  to  the  clustering  power  of  universal 
gravitation,  so  also  is  the  mystery  of  the  converse  problem  of  starless 
space,  which  was  a  subject  of  such  profound  meditation  by  the 
great  Herschel. 

18.  This  incomparable  astronomer  likewise  correctly  concluded 
that  the  breaking  up  of  the  Milky  Way  into  a  clustering  stream  is 
an  inevitable  effect  of  the  ravages  of  time ;  but  we  are  now  enabled 
to  foresee  the  restorative  process,  under  the  repulsive  forces  of  na- 
ture, by  which  new  nebulae,  clusters  and  sidereal  systems  of  high 
order  will  eventually  develop  in  the  present  depopulated  regions  of 
starless  space. 


632  THE  MONIST. 

19.  If  there  be  an  incessant  expulsion  of  dust  from  the  stars 
to  form  the  nebulae,  with  the  condensation  of  the  nebulae  into  stars 
and  stellar  systems,  while  the  gathering  of  stars  drawn  together 
by  a  clustering  power  operating  over  millions  of  ages  gives  at  length 
a  globular  mass  of  thousands  of  stars  accumulating  to  a  perfect 
blaze  of  starlight  in  the  center,  but  surrounded  externally  by  a  desert 
of  starless  space  resulting  from  the  ravages  of  time,  certainly  the 
building  of  these  magnificent  sidereal  systems  may  well  engage  the 
attention  of  the  natural  philosopher. 

20.  The  foremost  geometers  of  the  18th  century,  including  La- 
grange,  Laplace  and  Poisson,  were  greatly  occupied  with  the  prob- 
lem of  the  stability  of  the  solar  system ;  and  in  his  historical  eulogy 
on  Laplace  the  penetrating  Fourier  justly  remarks  that  the  researches 
of  geometers  prove  that  the  law  of  gravitation  itself  operates  as  a 
preservative  power,  and  renders  all  disorder  impossible,  so  that  no 
object  is  more  worthy  of  the  meditation  of  philosophers  than  the 
problem  of  the  stability  of  these  great  celestial  phenomena. 

But  if  the  question  of  the  stability  of  our  single  planetary  system 
may  so  largely  absorb  the  talents  of  the  most  illustrious  geometers 
of  the  age  of  Herschel,  how  much  more  justly  may  the  problem  of 
the  stability  of  clusters,  involving  many  thousands  of  such  systems, 
claim  the  attention  of  the  modern  geometer,  who  has  witnessed  the 
perfect  unfolding  of  the  grand  phenomena  first  discovered  by  that 
unrivaled  explorer  of  the  heavens? 

The  grandeur  of  the  study  of  the  origin  of  the  greatest  of  side- 
real systems  is  worthy  of  the  philosophic  penetration  of  a  Herschel ! 
The  solution  of  the  dynamical  problem  presented  surpasses  the 
powers  of  the  most  titanic  geometers,  and  would  demand  the  in- 
ventive genius  of  a  Newton  or  an  Archimedes! 

Yet  notwithstanding  the  transcendant  character  of  the  problem, 
and  the  hopelessness  of  a  rigorous  solution  in  our  time,  even  an  im- 
perfect outline  of  nature's  laws  may  aid  the  thoughtful  astronomer, 
in  penetrating  the  underlying  workings  of  the  sidereal  universe,  and 
thus  enable  him  to  perceive  the  great  end  subserved  by  the  develop- 
ment of  the  cosmos.  If  so,  he  may  well  rejoice,  and  exclaim  with 

Ptolemy : 

"Though  but  the  being  of  a  day, 
When  I  the  planet-paths  survey, 
My  feet  the  dust  despise; 
Up  to  the  throne  of  God  I  mount 
And  quaff  from  an  immortal  fount 
The  nectar  of  the  skies."— Transl.  by  W.  B.  Smith. 

T.  J.  J.  SEE. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  633 

THE  PROGRESS  OF  BUDDHIST  RESEARCH; 

WITH  SOMETHING  ABOUT  PENTECOST. 

Since  the  writing  of  my  note  on  the  "Buddhist-Christian  Miss- 
ing Link"  in  the  fall  of  1911  (Open  Court,  Chicago,  and  MaM 
Bodhi  Journal,  Colombo,  both  for  January,  1912),  great  events  have 
happened  in  the  field  of  Buddhist  learning.  We  are  now  hot  on 
the  trail  of  the  Missing  Link,  if  we  have  not  yet  found  it.  For,  be- 
sides the  selected  documents,  to  be  presently  described,  there  are 
thousands  more  reposing  in  the  libraries  of  Pekin,  London,  Paris  and 
Berlin,  which  we  know  to  contain  many  more  canonical  Sutras  trans- 
lated into  Sogdian,1  and  there  are  doubtless  more  forthcoming  in 
Bactrian  also.2 

In  a  book  published  in  1908,  I  said  this : 

"Menander,  in  the  second  century  before  Christ,  showed  an 
interest  in,  and  a  knowledge  of,  the  Buddhist  scriptures  which  may 
have  been  founded  upon  a  knowledge  of  Pali;  but  even  then  one 
would  expect  such  a  patron  to  have  some  specimens  of  the  lore  he 
admired  translated  into  Greek,  or  into  some  vernacular.  Strabo 
says  that  nearly  the  same  language  pervaded  Media  and  parts  of 
Persia,  Bactria  and  Sogdiana.  Strabo  also  says  that  the  Corybantes 
had  come  from  Bactria,  and  Euripides  pictures  them  as  passing 
the  Bactrian  Gates.  When  Buddhist  ideas  were  carried  westward, 
they  would  as  surely  be  translated  as  the  Bacchic  had  been." 

These  words  were  written  not  later  than  1907,  and  since  then 
my  prediction  has  been  abundantly  verified.  We  have  actually 
found  fragments  in  Chinese  Turkestan  of  Buddhist  scriptures  both 
in  Bactrian  and  Sogdian,  the  latter  coming  from  a  Chinese  library 
that  was  closed  up  in  1035,  while  documents  from  a  near-by  tower 
were  dated  A.D.  1  and  A.  D.20  !3  Bactrian  or  Tokharish  was  the 
language  of  ancient  Tukhara,  i.  e.,  northern  Afghanistan  and  parts 
of  Chinese  Turkestan.  Sogdian  was  spoken  in  Russian  Turkestan, 
where  the  city  of  Samarkand  had  been  the  center  of  a  Greek  civili- 
zation since  the  time  of  Alexander. 

In  Tokharish  we  have  found  Pacittiya  92  of  the  Vinaya,  in  the 
recension  of  the  Sarvastivadins,  thus  confirming  the  words  of  Yuan 

1 M.  Aurel  Stein,  Ruins  of  Desert  Cathay.    London,  1912,  Vol.  II,  p.  213. 

"  Sylvain  Levi,  in  Le  Temps,  Paris,  May  19,  1911.  Reprinted  in  the  Revue 
Archeologique. 

*  Stein,  Ruins  of  Desert  Cathay.  Among  these  documents,  though  un- 
dated, are  some  Sogdian  epistles  in  Aramaic  letters,  now  being  read  by  Gau- 
thiot. 


634  THE  MONIST. 

Chwang,  who  said  that  all  Tukhara  was  Sarvastivadin.  In  Sogdian 
we  have  found  the  Vessantara  Jataka,  that  great  favorite  about  the 
Bodhisat  prince  who  gave  all  he  had  away.4  It  was  this  very  Jataka 
that  was  graven  upon  the  Great  Tope  at  Anuradhapura,  when  vis- 
itors from  Alexandria  came  to  see  the  opening  ceremonies,  in  the 
second  century  before  Christ. 

Other  portions  of  scripture — the  Nidana  and  Dasabala  Sutras, 
the  Dharmapada — and  a  patristic  hymn,  have  been  found  in  San- 
skrit ;5  while  fragments  of  patristics  have  also  turned  up  in  Eastern 
Turkish,  written  in  characters  of  Syrian  origin,  side  by  side  with  a 
Christian  legend  about  the  Wise  Men  from  the  East  in  the  Gospel 
of  Matthew  !8 

All  this  means  that  in  the  early  centuries  of  the  Christian  era 
the  religion  of  the  Buddha  was  actively  at  work  in  languages  spoken 
by  the  Medes  and  Parthians  who  were  present  at  Jerusalem  in  the 
thirties  of  the  first  century  (Acts  ii.  9)  :  "Parthians  and  Medes  and 
Elamites,  and  the  dwellers  in  Mesopotamia,  in  Judea  and  Cappa- 
docia,  in  Pontus  and  Asia."  It  is  to  be  noted  that  Judea,  in  this 
verse,  is  tautological,  for  the  scene  narrated  is  laid  in  Judea.  As 
foreign  countries  are  being  represented,  we  must  probably  read 
India,  though  Dean  Alford  defends  our  present  text  on  geograph- 
ical grounds.  Now  the  New  Testament  writer  who  tells  us  this  is 
Luke,  the  Antioch  physician,  the  author  of  a  Gospel  whose  aim  was 
to  take  Christianity  outside  the  narrow  pale  of  Judaism  and  put  it 
into  line  with  the  Gentile  religions.  It  is  Luke  alone  who  has  the 
story  of  the  Penitent  Thief,  corresponding  to  the  Angulimalo  of 
the  Sutras.7  And  in  order  to  introduce  this  story  into  the  Gospel, 
Luke  is  compelled  to  violate  the  text  of  his  master  Mark,  who  says 
that  both  the  malefactors  reviled  the  Lord.  A  scholar  of  the  Eng- 
lish church,  in  a  recent  number  of  the  Hibbert  Journal,  has  shown 
that  Luke  was  utterly  unscrupulous  in  literary  matters,  and  again 
and  again  did  violence  to  his  sources  to  carry  out  his  aims.  I  have 
suggested,  both  in  my  Tokyo  edition  (1905)  and  in  my  Philadelphia 
edition  (1908)  that  Luke  did  violence  to  the  text  of  Mark  on  purpose 
to  introduce  these  Buddhist  legends  wherewith  he  was  familiar. 

It  is  true  that  our  present  Bactrian  and  Sogdian  manuscripts 

*  Gauthiot,  in  the  Paris  Journal  Asiatique,  January-February,  1912. 

'  Journal  Asiatique,  Nov.,-Dec.,  1910. 

9  Abhandlungen  of  the  Royal  Academy  of  Berlin,  1908  and  1911:  article 
"Uigurica,"  by  F.  W.  K.  Muller. 

7  Middling  Collection,  No.  86,  in  the  Pali ;  but  in  the  Numerical  Collection 
in  Chinese, 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  635 

are  probably  to  be  dated  between  the  third  century  and  the  eighth. 
But  this  is  in  Chinese  Turkestan,  whither  their  archetypes  had  been 
brought  from  regions  to  the  westward.  We  know,  from  coins  and 
from  Buddhist  history,  that  the  religion  was  flourishing  in  Bactria 
both  at  and  before  the  time  of  Christ;  and  the  inference  is  irresis- 
tible that,  when  the  missionaries  began  their  Chinese  translations 
in  the  sixties  of  the  first  century,  they  had  already  acquired  ex- 
perience as  translators  in  the  tongues  of  the  Parthian  empire.  The 
only  difference  is,  that  the  well-established  civilization  of  China,  and 
the  continuance  of  Buddhism  therein,  have  preserved  and  dated  the 
Chinese  versions,  whereas  the  extinction  of  Buddhism  by  Islam  in 
Afghanistan  and  elsewhere  has  destroyed  those  older  ones. 

What  we  have  actually  found  of  them  is  due  to  Chinese  care, 
in  Chinese  dominions ;  but  we  are  entitled  to  infer  a  whole  lost 
literature  in  Bactrian,  Sogdian  AND  GREEK,8  which  was  the 
vehicle  of  Buddhist  propaganda  in  the  days  of  the  Christian  Evan- 
gelists. 

We  do  not  need  to  wait  until  a  Greek  Sutra  is  dug  up  in  Af- 
ghanistan, as  I  have  hitherto  anticipated.  We  now  have  actually 
in  our  hands  a  series  of  Buddhist  documents  translated  by  mission- 
aries into  languages  that  were  understood  by  the  very  people  whom 
Luke  records  as  present  at  a  feast  which  his  authorities  had  wit- 
nessed. Could  we  but  find,  in  these  languages,  the  Buddhist  An- 
gelic Heralds  and  their  Hymn,  as  recorded  in  the  Sutta-Nipato ;  the 
Lord's  Three  Temptations,  viz.,  to  transmute  matter,  to  assume 
temporal  power  and  to  commit  suicide,  as  recorded  in  the  Classified 
and  Long  Collections;  the  Penitent  Brigand  aforesaid;  and  the 
Charge  to  the  Sixty-one  Missionaries,  so  like  Luke's  Charge  to  the 
Seventy,  we  should  have  in  our  hands  the  key  to  the  riddle  which 
Max  Miiller  said  he  had  spent  his  life  in  trying  to  solve;  viz.,  the 
indebtedness  of  our  proud  religion  of  humility  and  peace,  which 
has  been  spread  over  the  planet  by  the  swords  of  Europeans,  to  the 
meek  and  lowly  cult  of  our  brown  brethren  across  the  sea — that 
cult  which,  alone  among  the  faiths  of  mankind,  has  never  dipped 
its  hands  in  the  blood  of  animals  or  men. 

ALBERT  J.  EDMUNDS. 

PHILADELPHIA,  PA. 

"There  is  little  doubt  that  in  Bactria,  Buddhist  literature  was  actually 
translated  into  Greek."  (Buddhist  and  Christian  Gospels,  4th  ed.,  Philadel- 
phia, 1908-1909.  Vol.  I  (1908),  p.  154).  See  also  my  remarks  on  "that  lost 
version  of  the  Sutras  which  traveled  westward."  (Buddhist  Texts  in  John, 
1906,  pp.  26-28. 


636  THE  MONIST. 

BUDDHIST  LOANS  TO  CHRISTIANITY. 

WITH  SPECIAL  REFERENCE  TO  RICHARD  GARBE. 

SECOND  ARTICLE. 

To  my  remarks  in  The  Monist  and  The  Open  Court  for  January, 
1912,  I  should  like  to  add  a  few  words  to  congratulate  Professor 
Garbe  upon  the  conclusion  of  his  learned  monograph.  His  final 
summary  I  heartily  endorse,  except  that  I  would  modify  one  state- 
ment. The  following  is  the  paragraph  referred  to  (Monist,  April, 
1912,  p.  187) : 

"As  we  have  seen,  Christian  influences  upon  the  development 
of  Buddhism  are  limited  to  secondary  products  of  a  late  day;  just 
as  inversely  Buddhist  influences  upon  Christianity  may  be  pointed 
out  only  in  non-essential  particulars  and  from  times  in  which  the 
doctrine  of  the  Christian  faith  was  established  as  a  firm  system.  [  ] 
All  identities  and  similarities  in  the  teachings  of  these  two  great 
world-religions  have,  so  far  as  essential  matters  are  concerned,  orig- 
inated independently  of  one  another,  and  therefore  are  of  far  greater 
significance  for  the  science  of  religion  than  if  they  rested  upon  a 
loan." 

These  are  essentially  my  own  conclusions,  stated  many  times 
since  February,  1900 ;  but  I  would  add,  at  the  brackets,  the  words : 
[except  a  few  passages  of  minor  import  which  found  their  way  from 
organized  and  aggressive  Buddhism  into  formative  Christianity.} 

The  passages  especially  in  my  mind  are  the  Angelic  Heralds 
and  their  Hymn  in  Luke  ii ;  the  Lord's  Three  Temptations  in  Luke 
and  Matthew ;  two  texts  in  John  expressly  quoted  as  Law  and  Scrip- 
ture, but  not  found  in  the  Old  Testament  or  any  other  Jewish  book 
(John  vii.  38;  xii.  34)  ;  and  the  phrase  (eon-lasting  (or  "eternal") 
sin  at  Mark  iii.  29 — a  phrase  so  foreign  to  Christian  ideas  that  the 
copyists  altered  it  to  "eternal  damnation,"  as  Dean  Alford  admitted. 
Moreover,  as  said  in  Buddhist  and  Christian  Gospels  (Ed.  4,  vol.  1, 
p.  157),  Luke  was  probably  influenced  by  such  stories  as  the  Charge 
to  the  Sixty-one  Missionaries  (his  "Seventy")  and  the  Penitent 
Brigand.  As  shown  in  my  Tokyo  edition  (p.  48:  the  only  impor- 
tant passage  not  repeated  in  the  Philadelphia  one)  each  of  these 
stories  of  Luke  is  demonstrably  fiction,  and  he  moreover  can  be 
proved  to  have  altered  the  Marcan  or  Synoptic  tradition  to  suit  his 
own  ideas  (as  in  Mark  xvi.  7  =  Luke  xxiv.  6).  To  my  mind  the 
case  is  precisely  analogous  to  that  of  the  moons  of  Uranus  being 
perturbed  by  the  presence  of  Neptune. 


CRITICISMS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.  637 

When  in  Philadelphia  last  fall,  Franz  Cumont  told  us  that  there 
is  a  set  of  technical  phrases  in  ancient  Greek  books  on  astrology 
which  have  now  been  shown  to  be  literal  translations  from  the 
Babylonian.  In  precisely  the  same  way,  such  Buddhist  phrases  as 
(^on-lasting  sin  and  others  gained  similar  currency  among  the  an- 
cients, who  persistently  sought  out  the  distinctive  teachings  of  the 
great  nations,  just  as  we  do  now. 

With  these  reservations,  I  wish,  as  a  student  of  Buddhism,  to 
give  my  most  cordial  adhesion  to  the  conclusions  of  the  learned 
Brahmin  scholar,  who  has  dealt  with  a  knotty  problem  in  a  masterly 
manner  and  summarized  the  researches  of  many  specialists. 

PHILADELPHIA,  PA.  ALBERT  J.  EDMUNDS. 

A  POSTSCRIPT  TO  INDO-ROMAN  RELATIONS  IN  THE 
FIRST  CENTURY. 

In  The  Monist  for  December,  1911,  Professor  Garbe  denied  the 
existence  of  Buddhist  loans  to  canonical  Christianity,  and  gave  as 
one  of  his  reasons  the  following  question  and  answer: 

"Do  the  evidences  of  intercommunication  at  all  permit  the 
assumption*  that  as  early  as  the  first  century  after  Christ,  or 
earlier,  Buddhist  legends  and  ideas  had  found  their  way  into 

Palestine? 

"They  are  not  apt  to  raise  this  possibility  to  a  serviceable 
degree  of  probability  for  as  early  a  period  as  the  first  post- 
Christian  century." 

To  this  assertion  I  replied  in  the  following  number,  avoiding 
reference  to  the  canonical  literature,  which  was  simultaneously  con- 
sidered by  my  friend  Mr.  Albert  J.  Edmunds,  but  assembling  various 
evidences  of  a  large,  important  and  rapidly  increasing  intercommuni- 
cation between  Rome  and  India  during  the  first  century  of  the  Chris- 
tian era,  as  indicating  the  possibility  of  the  assumption  which  Pro- 
fessor Garbe  had  outlined. 

In  The  Monist  for  July,  1912,  in  a  postscript  to  his  most  in- 
structive discussion,  Professor  Garbe  acknowledges  the  probability 
of  closer  intercommunication  than  he  has  heretofore  admitted,  and 
accepts  one  of  the  canonical  parallels  offered  by  Mr.  Edmunds ;  but 
he  thinks  that  I  "beg  the  question"  by  assuming  the  possibility  of  an 
interchange  of  ideas  as  well  as  goods. 

To  this  objection  I  would  reply  that  I  was  but  addressing  my- 

1  Italics  mine. 


638  THE  MONIST. 

self  to  the  assumption  which  he  had  declared  to  be  unwarranted ;  so 
that  if  there  has  been  any  begging  of  the  question  it  would  seem  to 
have  been  in  the  same  degree  on  each  side  of  the  discussion. 

Professor  Garbe  objects  to  any  citation  of  the  Periplus  because 
it  does  not  mention  religion;  but  the  citation  was  merely  to  show 
the  existence  of  an  active  commerce,  and  it  is  well  known  that  the 
missionary  and  the  trader  have  gone  close  together  in  many  ages 
of  the  world.  They  have  not  always  respected  one  another,  but  they 
have  usually  followed  the  same  paths.  Surely  Professor  Garbe  would 
not  expect  a  future  historian  of  our  own  times  to  deny  the  assump- 
tion of  Christian  missions  in  China  because  some  surviving  consular 
report  on  the  Shanghai  trade  might  omit  a  reference  to  the  Nicene 
Creed! 

Professor  Garbe  objects,  also,  that  the  Hindu  traders  to  the 
Roman  Empire  were  Dravidians  and  stupid,  and  therefore  not  likely 
to  talk  of  their  religion.  But  in  the  first  century  of  our  era  they 
were  increasingly  Indo-Scythian,  from  a  portion  of  India  that  pro- 
fessed a  liberal  and  proselytizing  Buddhism,  and  I  repeat  that  for 
that  date  and  race,  a  spreading  of  ideas  together  with  an  interchange 
of  goods,  was  not  only  a  possible  assumption,  but  a  probable  fact. 

The  extent  of  such  intercommunication  is  made  much  more 
evident  by  Mr.  J.  Kennedy's  paper  "The  Secret  of  Kanishka,"  begun 
in  the  Journal  of  the  Royal  Asiatic  Society  for  July  1912.  The  long- 
drawn  discussion  as  to  the  so-called  Vikrama  era  of  58  B.  C.  seems 
brought  to  a  reasonable  conclusion  through  Mr.  Kennedy's  brilliant 
assembling  of  Chinese  and  numismatic  evidence.  It  was  the  era 
of  the  second  Buddhist  Council  and  of  the  Kushan  king  Kanishka. 
His  power  over  northwestern  India,  built  up  by  his  control  of  the 
transcontinental  silk-trade,  was  fortified  by  his  becoming  the  pro- 
tector of  the  Buddhist  faith ;  and  under  him  and  his  immediate  suc- 
cessors, just  before  the  Christian  era,  it  is  highly  probable  that  his 
faith  was  expounded  to  the  east  as  far  as  Turfan,  and  to  the  west 
as  far  as  Charax  Spasini,  Antioch  and  Alexandria. 

The  truth  is,  that  during  the  period  between  50  B.  C.  and  100 
A.  D.,  approximately,  India  was  a  leading  factor  in  the  world's 
thought,  industry,  commerce,  and  wealth;  and,  this  being  the  case, 
to  repeat  Professor  Garbe's  own  words,  "the  evidences  of  intercom- 
munication permit  the  assumption  of  the  migration  of  Buddhist 
legends  and  ideas  into  Palestine  as  early  as  the  first  century  after 
Christ."  WILFRED  H.  SCHOFF. 

PHILADELPHIA,  PA. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  AND  NOTES. 

THE  RELIGION  OF  THE  IRANIAN  PEOPLES.  By  C.  P.  Tide.  Part  I  (From  the 
German).  With  Darmesteter's  Sketch  of  "Persia,"  and  Goldziher's  "In- 
fluence of  Parsism  on  Islam"  (From  the  French).  Translated  by  G.  K. 
Nariman.  Bombay:  Parsi  Publishing  Co.,  1912. 

G.  K.  Nariman,  who  is  known  to  readers  of  the  Revue  de  I'Histoire  des 
Religions  and  other  magazines,  is  a  Parsi  scholar  who  is  also  acquainted  at 
first-hand  with  Buddhism,  both  from  its  Pali  and  its  Sanskrit  sides.  Indeed, 
one  of  the  features  of  this  excellent  translation  is  an  appendix  by  the  trans- 
lator entitled,  "Some  Buddhistic  Parallels."  The  subjects  dealt  with  are:  (i) 
the  triple  formula:  body,  speech  and  mind;  (2)  Buddhist  allusions  to  con- 
sanguineous marriages;  (3)  Hindu  exposure  of  the  dead,  as  described  in  the 
Pitakas;  (4)  Mara  and  Ahriman;  (5)  questions  addressed  to  Mazda  and 
Buddha;  (6)  the  idea  of  a  counterfeit  creation  (Parsi)  or  a  counterfeit  re- 
ligion (Buddhist)  ;  (7)  the  use  of  the  name  Ormazd  by  Turanian  Buddhists; 
(8)  the  killing  of  noxious  creatures  by  the  Kambojas;  and  some  other  points. 

The  following  note  on  the  Turkish  Buddhist  literature  recently  found  in 
Central  Asia  deserves  reprinting: 

"Ein  in  turkischer  Sprache  bearbeitetes  buddhistisches  Sutra,  by  Radloff 
and  Stael-Holstein  (St.  Petersburg,  1910).  This  important  work  is  typical  of 
the  avoidable  Babel  which  Western  philologists  seem  unfortunately  determined 
to  create  in  their  otherwise  fascinating  field  of  marvelous  investigations.  The 
original  text  is  in  the,  up  to  now,  almost  unknown  Uigurian,  which  the  Russian 
scholars  have  made  accessible  to  us  through  a  German  translation;  but  the 
transliteration  is  in  Russian  character,  and  the  interesting  notes  on  the  Brahmi 
gloss  are  made  unserviceable  to  the  average  student  of  Buddhism  by  the 
introduction  of  two  sets  of  unknown  alphabets,  besides  Chinese,  Arabic  and 
Nagari  scripts.  Eastern  students,  however,  must  be  grateful  to  the  Imperial 
Academy  of  Sciences,  St.  Petersburg,  for  the  employment  of  the  Nagari  char- 
acter in  the  publication  of  its  admirable  series  of  Bibliotheca  Buddhica" 

It  is  studies  like  this  which  help  to  break  down  the  former  provincialism 
of  religious  treatises,  wherein  (to  borrow  a  phrase  of  Cumont's)  each  religion 
was  regarded  as  an  experiment  in  a  closed  vessel. 

We  could  wish  that  the  learned  translator  had  had  a  little  more  regard 
to  the  naturalization  of  Oriental  adjectives,  and  so  given  us  the  familiar  Eng- 
lish forms  Achcemenian,  Sassanian,  instead  of  Achcemenide ,  Sassanide.  The 
lack  of  diacritical  marks  is  also  confusing.  But  such  small  flaws  by  no 


640  THE  MONIST. 

means  detract  from  the  great  value  of  Tide's  able  essay  in  an  English  dress, 
accompanied  by  the  other  essays  indicated,  which  make  the  little  book  an 
interesting  companion  for  the  student  of  Comparative  Religion. 

ALBERT  J.  EDMUNDS. 


ALTUTONISH    (PANGERMAN).  BEI   ELIAS   MOLEE.      TaCOma,    IQII.      PagCS   32. 

The  advocate  of  a  new  language  called  "altutonish"  or  "pangerman"  to- 
gether with  an  abolition  of  all  capital  letters  is  vigorously  continued  by 
"elias  molee,  ph.  b.,  1554  'd'  street,  tacoma,  wash.,  u,  s.  a."  by  sending  out  a 
pamphlet  containing  exercises  in  his  new  language  which  he  characterizes 
as  "  ein  (a)  union  spiek  (language),  makn  up  ov  deuch,  english,  skandinavish 
and  hollandi,  for  to  agenfererein  (re-unite)  al  tutonish  folka  (people)  into 
ein  spiek  mitin  (within)  feivti  (50)  jiera  (years)." 

He  believes  that  the  world  is  mainly  Teutonic  and  that  a  combination  of 
all  Teutonic  languages  should  be  the  best  international  language.  As  a  motto 
he  selects  a  word  of  Victor  Hugo,  who  has  said  somewhere:  "The  German 
character  hovers  over  the  nations,"  or  as  it  reads  in  German:  "Die  deutsche 
Natur  schwebt  ilber  den  Volkern" 

Such  a  combination  might  have  been  possible  at  the  time  the  English 
language  originated  after  the  Norman  conquest  through  the  breakdown  of  the 
literal  Anglo  Saxon;  but  times  are  changed  through  the  wide-spread  use  of 
written  and  printed  language  which  has  added  power  to  the  resistance  of  the 
established  language  such  as  was  impossible  in  the  times  when  language  was 
still  purely  speech,  when  it  was  limited  to  the  spoken  word  which  is  more 
flexible  and  would  admit  easily  of  radical  changes.  K 


Readers  of  The  Monist  will  be  interested  to  hear  that  Prof.  Hugo  de  Vries 
is  making  another  visit  to  the  United  States  this  autumn.  He  reached  New 
York  about  September  12,  where  he  was  to  give  a  lecture  at  the  Botanical 
Garden  on  September  14.  From  there  he  goes  to  the  University  of  Pennsyl- 
vania to  see  the  work  which  Professor  Davis  is  doing  with  Oenotheras,  and 
then  spends  a  short  time  in  Washington.  His  next  objective  point  is  Dixie 
Landing,  Ala.,  where  he  goes  with  Professor  Tracy  to  visit  the  type  locality 
of  Oenothera  grandiflora  to  study  its  possible  mutants  in  its  original  habitat. 
He  then  goes  to  Biloxi,  Miss.,  where  he  will  make  his  headquarters  while 
visiting  the  "mud  lumps"  near  the  mouth  of  the  Mississippi  River,  and  a 
number  of  islands  near  Biloxi.  After  that  he  and  Professor  Tracy  will  go 
to  San  Antonio,  Brownsville,  and  other  points  in  southern  Texas,  where 
Professor  de  Vries  goes  to  study  the  relation  of  the  flora  to  the  geological  and 
geographical  conditions.  On  October  14,  Professor  de  Vries  is  to  deliver  the 
dedicatory  address  of  the  Rice  Institute,  at  Houston,  Texas. 


B 
1 

M7 
v.22 


The  Monist 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
CARDS  OR  SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 


UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO  LIBRARY