Skip to main content

Full text of "Morals: a treatise on the psycho-sociological bases of ethics"

See other formats


LIBRARY 

OF    THE 

UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA. 


.Class 


THE  CONTEMPORAR  Y  SCIENCE  SERIES. 
EDITED  BY  HAVELOCK  ELLIS. 


MORALS: 

A    TREATISE    ON    THE    PSYCHO-SOCIOLOGICAL 
BASES   OF   ETHICS. 


MORALS: 

A  TREATISE  ON  THE 

PSYCHO-SOCIOLOGICAL  BASES 
OF  ETHICS. 


BY 


PROFESSOR  G.  L.   DUPRAT. 


TRANSLATED    BY 


W.  J.   GREENSTREET,   M.A.,   F.R.A.S. 


THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  CO.,  LTD., 

LONDON   AND   NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 

1903. 


73  J7  32 


PREFACE. 


THE  field  of  psychological  research  has  widened  by 
the  triple  alliance  of  psychology,  physiology,  and 
sociology — an  alliance  at  once  of  the  most  intimate 
and  fundamental  nature,  and  productive  of  far- 
reaching  results.  It  need,  therefore,  occasion  no 
surprise  that  among  the  volumes  of  a  scientific 
series  is  to  be  found  a  treatise  dealing  with  ethical 
questions.  No  doubt  it  is  true  that  ethics  and 
metaphysics  have  up  to  the  present  been  closely 
interwoven.  Under  the  guise  of  ethical  theory, 
philosophical  speculations  of  the  most  audacious 
type  -are  presented  to  the  student.  But  recent 
works  on  ethics  have  not  been  numerous,  and 
betray  signs  of  lassitude  in  those  metaphysicians 
who  paraphrase  in  general  terms  the  works  of  Kant, 
and  seem  more  anxious  to  soar  into  the  realms  of 
lofty  thought  than  to  lay  the  foundations  of  work 
that  will  be  both  positive  and  lasting.  It  would 
seem  that  the  time  has  come  for  a  system  of  ethics 
less  ambitious  in  its  aims,  more  restricted  in  its 
scope,  and  based  on  a  more  rigorous  method  of 
treatment.  To  build  and  complete  the  temple  of 


VI  PREFACE. 

positive  morality  is  beyond  our  power,  but  we  are 
able,  at  any  rate,  to  claim  for  the  psychologist  and 
the  sociologist  the  exclusive  right  of  supplying  the 
moralist  with  the  material  for  the  foundations  of  his 
ethical  doctrine. 

In  the  near  future  it  will,  no  doubt,  be  a  matter 
of  surprise  that  men  were  so  pretentious  as  to 
teach  morals,  and  to  direct  the  most  complex  of 
all  activities,  without  having  made,  as  a  preliminary, 
a  sufficiently  exhaustive  study  of  man  and  of  society. 
We  shall  be  amazed  at  the  subjectivity  of  moral 
conceptions,  even  while  we  remember  that  they 
were  the  work  of  the  greatest  minds  of  every  age; 
at  assertions  based  on  incomplete  and  even  in- 
accurate notions  of  individual  and  social  life;  at 
precepts  of  value  to  the  individual  alone,  enunciated 
by  him  for  the  purpose  of  justifying  his  manner  of 
life,  systematised  "  after  the  event,"  when  prejudices 
and  preconceived  ideas  have  had  their  natural  effect 
on  a  mind  which  then  offers  itself,  more  or  less 
unconsciously,  as  a  model  to  its  contemporaries  and 
their  descendants ! 

Plato,  with  his  aristocratic  and  Athenian  tastes — 
Aristotle,  saturated  with  intellectualism — Descartes, 
oscillating  between  science  and  religion — Spinoza,  a 
fatalist  and  mystic, — each  in  turn  has  described  the 
moral  ideal  according  to  his  own  temperament  and 
personal  tendencies,  and  this  they  have  done  in 
almost  complete  self-absorption,  as  if  assured  that 
all  other  mortals  were  fashioned  like  unto  them, 


PREFACE.  Vll 

and  that  they  themselves  were  the  noblest  types  of 
humanity. 

For  centuries  it  has  seemed  that  morals  could 
alone  be  taught  by  the  "  Beyond-man,"  chosen  of 
God  to  guide  his  fellows,  a  being  instantaneously 
inspired,  laying  down  precepts  of  wisdom,  the  value 
of  which  was  entirely  dependent  on  their  beauty  and 
elevation  of  thought.  It  necessarily  followed  that 
the  foundations  on  which  these  precepts  were  based 
could  not  be  brought  to  the  touchstone  of  criticism 
—they  were  the  inspirations  of  genius,  and  sprang 
from  the  depths  of  the  unconscious;  like  the  con- 
ceptions of  the  artist,  they  could  attract  and  seduce 
by  appealing  to  the  heart  rather  than  to  the  reason. 

It  was  not  long,  however,  before  those  psycho- 
logists who  had  appealed  to  mental  disorders  for 
light  on  the  conditions  of  normal  life,  rounded  off 
their  purely  scientific  researches  by  practical  appli- 
cations in  the  domains  of  both  politics  and  morals. 
Italian  anthropology  has  linked  by  the  closest  ties 
the  theory  of  law,  of  sanction,  and  of  crime  to 
psychology  and  psychiatry;  sociology  has  taken  its 
place  among  the  positive  sciences,  and  its  relation 
to  ethics  is  beyond  dispute. 

But  we  can  only  link  together  psychology  and 
sociology  by  admitting  the  mixed,  the  psycho- 
sociological,1  character  of  most  of  the  sentiments 

1  Cf.  my  Rapports  de  la  Psychologic  et  de  /a  Sociologie  (Imprimerie 
Nationale,  1899)  and  Science  Sociale  et  Democratic  (Giard  et  Briere, 
1900). 


Vlll  PREFACE. 

and  ideas  that  the  moralist  has  to  take  into 
consideration. 

It  is  no  longer  necessary  to  examine  these  senti- 
ments and  ideas  from  the  point  of  view  of  this  or 
that  moral  theory.  And  as,  on  the  one  hand,  their 
psycho-sociological  nature  makes  them  functions  of 
social  life  and  of  the  collective  future;  and  as,  on 
the  other  hand,  the  concrete  being  is  the  being 
which  lives  in  society,  and  with  it  ethics  is  neces- 
sarily concerned,  it  follows  that  the  sociologist  must 
share  his  task  with  the  psychologist.  Whoever, 
therefore,  wishes  to  lay  down  rules  for  the  guidance 
of  the  conduct  of  his  fellow-creatures  must  be  a 
savant  before  he  is  a  moralist;  he  must  at  least  be 
in  a  position  to  avail  himself  of  the  scientific  data 
which  are  placed  at  his  service  by  individual  and 
social  psychology.  He  must  realise  the  inevitable 
transformation  of  the  moralist  from  the  "  sage  "  or 
the  "  seer "  to  the  man  of  science.  The  doctor- 
philosopher  of  to-day,  who,  following  men  like 
Charcot,  Ribot,  and  Janet,  has  introduced  into 
psychology  an  entirely  new  spirit,  now  applies  to 
the  moral  life  the  really  scientific  knowledge  he  has 
acquired  in  his  clinical  work,  in  the  laboratory,  in 
the  hospital,  and  in  the  asylum;  he  thus  welds 
together  two  links  in  a  chain— and  even  now  the 
necessity  is  not  sufficiently  realised— the  study  of 
nervous  or  mental  diseases  and  the  struggle  against 
social  diseases — i.e.,  against  immorality. 

The  reader  cannot  expect  that  in  a  volume  such 


PREFACE.  IX 

as  this  human  conduct  can  be  treated  other  than 
as  a  whole.  To  go  into  detail,  to  justify  every 
assertion,  to  deduce  every  consequence,  would 
necessitate  volumes  of  considerable  size.  But, 
quite  apart  from  that,  no  single  individual  could 
be  found  sufficiently  competent  to  undertake  the 
task.  This  volume,  therefore,  contains  but  a  general 
view  of  the  foundations  of  ethics,  and  of  some  of 
the  directing  ideas  of  "really  human  "  conduct.  On 
many  points,  no  doubt,  knowledge  is  still  lacking; 
on  many  others  the  science  of  to-morrow  will  throw 
doubt  on  the  assertions  which  are  supported  by  the 
science  of  to-day.  No  one  in  these  matters  can 
boast  with  respect  to  any  formula  for  which  he  is 
responsible — ne  varietur.  Let  each  reader  amend 
what  he  reads  to  the  best  of  his  ability.  A  moral 
theory  is  proposed  and  not  imposed;  but  when  it 
is  propounded  in  the  name  of  science,  there  can  be 
produced  in  its  defence  stronger  scientific  evidence 
than  is  available  for  the  purpose  of  those  who  attack, 
or  amend,  or  complete  it. 

G.  L.  DUPRAT. 


CONTENTS. 

PART  I. 
THE   METHOD. 

FAGIi 

I.  ETHICS,  METAPHYSICS,  AND  RELIGION  ...         2 

i.  The  Moral  Crisis — 2.  Morals  in  the  Ancient  World 
— 3.  Moral  Philosophy — 4.  Powerlessness  of  Philo- 
sophy— 5.  Powerlessness  of  Religion — 6.  Conditions 
of  Morality. 

II.  SCIENTIFIC  MORALITY   ...         ...         ...         ...       12 

7.  Independent  Ethics— 8.  The  Science  of  Ethics— 
9.  Kantian  Ethics  and  its  Postulates— 10.  Science  and 
Ethics— ii.  The  Real  and  the  Ideal — 12.  The  Tech- 
nical Character  of  Morality — 13.  Spiritualism,  Idealism, 
and  Naturalism — 14.  Morals  as  a  Technical  Process. 

III.  INDIVIDUAL  AND  SOCIAL  ETHICS         26 

15.  The  Arts  and  Ethics— 16.  Social  Ethics-i;.  The 
Moral  Consciousness — 18.  The  Data  of  Reason — 
19.  Rational  Conduct — 20.  Duty  and  Moral  Worth — 

21.  Individual  Dignity. 

* 

IV.  THE    DIFFERENT    MODES    OF    ETHICAL    RE- 

SEARCH                4° 

22.  The  Kantian  Method — 23.   Plato  and  Aristotle— 
24.    Adam    Smith — 25.    Spencer — 26.    Conclusion    on 
Method. 


Xll  CONTENTS. 

PART  II. 
THE   PSYCHOLOGICAL   IDEAL. 

PAGE 

I.  THE  MORAL  WILL        52 

27.  Pure  Practical  Reason  —  28.  Moral  Action, 
Voluntary  Action — 29.  Perception,  Conception,  and 
Imagination  —  30.  Attention  and  Association  — 31. 
Perception  and  the  Sensorial  Type — 32.  Self-per- 
ception— 33.  Instability  and  Aboulia— 34.  Deliberation 
— 35.  The  Conscious  Processes — 36.  Irreflection  and 
Good  Manners — 37-The  Choice  of  the  Best — 38.  Priority 
of  the  Tendency  over  the  Idea  of  the  Good— 39.  Moral 
Subjectivism  —  40.  Unification  of  Tendencies  and 
Heredity  — 41.  The  Reason  —  42.  The  Union  of 
Different  Tendencies  and  of  Reason. 

II.  LIBERTY  AND  MORALITY          80 

43.  Kant  and  Free-will — 44.  The  Origin  of  Character 
— 45.  Science,  Conscience,  and  Liberty — 46.  Belief 
and  Liberty — 47.  The  Person  the  Real  Agent — 48. 
Conclusion. 

III.  THE  MORAL  TENDENCIES         94 

49.  Different  Tendencies,  Different  Doctrines — 50. 
Naturalism  —  51.  Hedonism  —  52.  Epicureanism  —  53. 
Utilitarianism — 54-  Interest  and  Desire — 55-  Egoism 
—  56.  The  Collective  Interest— -57.  Intellectual  Happi- 
ness— 58.  Mysticism — 59.  The  Ethics  of  Spinoza — 60. 
The  Stoic  Morality— 61.  The  Esthetic  Sentiment — 
62.  The  Altruistic  Tendencies — 63.  Generosity — 64. 
Sociability — 65.  Tendency  to  Social  Organisation. 

IV.  THE  MORAL  INDIVIDUAL         135 

66.  The  Psychological  Ideal  and  Moral  Firmness — 67. 
Moderation — 68.  Virtue  and  Truth— 69.  The  Cult  of 
the  Beautiful— 70.  Joy— 71.  Risk  and  Exercise. 


CONTENTS.  Xlll 

PAGE 

V.  THE  DETERMINISM  OF  IMMORAL  ACTIONS  ....     152 

72.  Crime — 73.  Crime  and  the  Criminal — 74.  Classifi- 
cation and  Descriptive  Summary— 75.  The  Criminal 
by  Accident — 76.  Insane  Criminals — 77.  Immorality 
of  the  Imbecile — 78.  Intelligent  Degenerates — 79.  The 
Unbalanced— 80.  The  Criminal  by  Passion— 8 1.  The 
Obsessed— 82.  Exaggeration  of  Good  Sentiments— 
83.  Moral  Vertigo  —  84.  The  Criminal  Type  —  85. 
Immoral  Effects  of  Solidarity — 86.  Effects  of  Heredity, 
Alcoholism,  and  Social  Disturbances  in  General. 


PART  III. 

THE  SOCIAL  IDEAL. 

I.  SOCIAL  EVOLUTION         189 

87.  The  Present  State  of  Sociology— 88.  Social  Statics 
and  Dynamics — 89.  The  Evolution  of  the  Family — 
90.  The  Matriarchate  and  the  Primitive  Condition  of 
Woman — 91.  The  Primitive  Condition  of  Children — 92. 
The  "Patria  Potestas"  and  the  Dissolution  of  the 
Family — 93.  The  Future  of  the  Family — 94.  Animal 
Societies — 95.  Political  Life  and  the  Struggle  of  Classes 
— 96.  The  Idea  of  Equality — 97.  Governments — 
98.  Plutocracy — 99.  Political  Evolution  and  Law — 

100.  The  Law  of  Contract. 

II.  SOCIAL  EVOLUTION  (continued}  215 

101.  The  Primitive  Economic  State — 102.   Economic 
Evolution — 103.  Division  of  Labour — 104.  Association 
— 105.     Slavery    and    Property — 106.     Property — 107. 
Capital  and  Labour — 108.  Collective  Sentiments — 109. 
Differentiation  of  the  Primitive  Sentiments — no.   The 
Evolution    of    Sociability — in.     The     Religion     of 
Humanity  and  of  the  Unknowable— 112.  Sociological 
Anticipations, 


XIV  CONTENTS. 

PAGE 

III.  THE  SOCIAL  IDEAL        235 

113.  Individualism  and  Altruism — 114.  The  Over- 
Man— 115.  Sacrifice  of  the  Unfit— 116.  The  Gospel  of 
Tolstoi— 117.  Renunciation— 1 18.  The  Consequences 
of  Non-resistance  to  Evil — 119.  The  Necessity  of  Con- 
flict—120.  Despotism— 121.  The  Meek— 122.  The 
Aristocracy — 123.  Importance  of  the  Theory  of  Rights. 

IV.  RIGHTS 257 

124.  The  Foundation  of  Rights — 125.  Natural  Right — 
126.  Metaphysical  Right  and  Dignity — 127.  Rights 
of  Social  Function — 128.  Justice  and  Devotion — 
129.  Justice  and  Charity— 130.  The  Right  of  Property 
— 131.  The  Share  of  the  Community — 132.  Property 
and  Reform — 133.  The  Hereditary  Transmission  of 
Property. 

V.  THE  STATE         274 

134.  The  Role  of  the  State— 135.  Theories  of  Sover- 
eignty—136.  Summary  of  the  Theories — 137.  Relative 
Sovereignty  and  the  Social  Contract— 138.  Duties  of 
the  State — 139.  The  State  and  Associations — 140.  The 
State  as  Educator — 141.  The  State  as  Judge. 

VI.  THE  ECONOMIC  ORGANISATION  292 

142.  Competition — 143.  Subordination  of  the  Economic 
Order  to  a  Higher  Order—  144.  The  Role  of  the  State 
— 145.  The  State  Principle  and  the  Corvee — 146. 
Taxation — 147.  Solidarity  in  the  Economic  Order — 
148.  The  Wages  System  — 149.  Co-operation — 150. 
The  Work  of  Women  and  Children— 151.  Value  of 
the  Workman — 152.  The  Choice  of  a  Profession  — 153. 
The  Rights  and  Duties  of  the  Workman. 

VI I.  THE  FAMILY,  FRIENDSHIP,  AND   THE  COLLEC- 
TIVE SENTIMENTS 314 

154.  The  Rights  of  Woman— 155.  Marriage— 156. 
The  Co-Education  and  Equality  of  the  Sexes — 157. 


CONTENTS.  XV 

I'AGF. 

Divorce  arid  Duties  towards  Children— 158.  Duties  of 
Children — 159.  Friendship  and  Fraternity — 160.  Man 
in  Relation  to  Animals — 161.  Genuine  Human  Senti- 
ments. 


PART  IV. 
THE  STRUGGLE  AGAINST  IMMORALITY. 

I.  SOCIAL  RESPONSIBILITY.  334 

162.  Conditions  of  Responsibility.  Intention — 163. 
Errors  of  Appreciation — 164.  Insufficient  Deliberation 
— 165.  Irresponsibility — 166.  Possible  Modification  of 
the  Character — 167.  Imputability — 168.  Social  Action. 

II.  SANCTION  AND  MORAL  EDUCATION    ...         ...     352 

169.  Role  and  Nature  of  Sanction — 170.  Happiness 
the  Natural  Consequence  of  Moral  Action — 171. 
Merit — 172.  The  Immorality  of  Punishment — 173. 
Utilitarian  Role  of  Punishment — 174.  Moral  Sugges- 
tion. 

BIBLIOGRAPHY  ...         ...         ...         ...         ...         ...     371 

INDEX 375 


MORALS: 

THEIR    PSYCHO-SOCIOLOGICAL    BASES, 


PART   I. 

THE  METHOD. 

I.  ETHICS,  METAPHYSICS,  AND  RELIGION. 

i.  The  Moral  Crisis — 2.  Morals  in  the  Ancient  World 
— 3.  Moral  Philosophy — 4.  Powerlessness  of  Philosophy 
—  5.  Powerlessness  of  Religion  —  6.  Conditions  of 
Morality. 

II.  SCIENTIFIC  MORALITY. 

7.  Independent  Ethics — 8.  The  Science  of  Ethics — 9. 
Kantian  Ethics  and  its  Postulates — 10.  Science  and 
Ethics—  n.  The  Real  and  the  Ideal— 12.  The  Technical 
Character  of  Morality —  1 3.  Spiritualism^  Idealism,  and 
Naturalism — 14.  Morals  as  a  Technical  Process. 

III.  INDIVIDUAL  AND  SOCIAL  ETHICS. 

15.  The  Arts  and  Ethics— 16.  Social  Ethics— 17.  The 
Moral  Consciousness — 18.  The  Data  of  Reason — 19. 
Rational  Conduct — 20.  Duty  and  Moral  Worth — 21. 
Individual  Dignity. 

IV.  THE  DIFFERENT  MODES  OF  ETHICAL  RESEARCH. 

22.  The  Kantian  Method— 23.  Plato  and  Aristotle — 
24.  Adam  Smith — 25.  Spencer — 26.  Conclusion  on 
Method. 

I 


2  ETHICS,    METAPHYSICS,   AND    RELIGION. 

I. 

ETHICS,  METAPHYSICS,  AND  RELIGION. 

i.  The  Moral  Crisis. 

As  the  spirit  of  criticism  develops,  as  simple  faith, 
superstitions,  and  even  traditions  lose  their  influence 
over  the  masses,  and  as  the  increasing  complexity 
of  social,  political,  and  economical  relations  involves 
more  instability,  more  risk  of  disorder  and  dis- 
aggregation,  we  more  and  more  appreciate,  from  the 
constant  increase  of  crime,  the  dangers  of  moral 
anarchy. 

During  the  whole  of  the  nineteenth  century  the 
evolution  of  ideas  and  collective  sentiments,  the 
increase  in  the  number  of  publications  of  every 
kind — books,  pamphlets,  journals,  etc. — and  of  public 
lectures,  have  introduced  into  the  great  current  of 
popular  thought  a  considerable  number  of  practical 
conceptions,  which  are,  however,  conflicting  and 
often  irreconcilable.  Our  age  is  an  age  of 
criticism ;  the  foundations  of  law  have  been  called 
in  question,  and  those  of  traditional  law,  in  parti- 
cular, have  been  destroyed;  the  family,  the  city, 
civil  and  religious  society  have  been  profoundly 
modified  in  the  course  of  a  single  century.  Reli- 
gious faith  has  ceased  to  play  the  important  r6le 
which  seemed  to  have  devolved  upon  it ;  on  every 
side  it  is  disappearing,  or  at  any  rate  is  ceasing  to 
be  an  obstacle  to  immorality.  And  in  the  same 
manner  the  "  social  conscience,"  if  we  may  use  this 
term  to  designate  the  sum-total  of  conceptions  and 
sentiments  which  are  common  to  a  whole  race, 


MORALS    IN    THE    ANCIENT   WORLD.  3 

seems  to  be  in  a  state  of  hesitation,  wavering,  and 
uncertainty,  and  to  be  passing  through  stages  of 
groping  in  the  dark,  of  sudden  shock,  and  of  perilous 
crisis. 

There  seems  to  be  nothing  to  guarantee  stability 
in  morals;  the  ideas  of  good  and  evil,  of  justice 
and  injustice,  of  what  is  lawful  and  what  is  for- 
bidden, seem  more  and  more  arbitrary,  and  to 
have  a  merely  conventional  or  even  a  provisional 
value. 

2.  Morals  in  the  Ancient  World. 

Was  not  the  existence  of  this  state  of  confusion 
inevitable,  and  was  it  not,  after  all,  for  the  best? 
When  "  social  disintegration "  had  reached  its 
maximum  in  ancient  Greece,  two  ethical  doctrines, 
which  have  persisted  as  types  to  the  present  day, 
made  their  appearance,  and  were  favourably  re- 
ceived by  those  who  had  remained  unaffected  by  the 
subtle  dialectic  of  Plato  or  the  masterly  metaphysic 
of  Aristotle. 

In  the  realm  of  morals,  it  was  not  long  before 
Stoicism  and  Epicureanism  became  rivals  throughout 
the  civilised  world,  and  philosophical  conceptions 
became  definitely  supreme  in  ethics. 

Stoicism,  it  is  true,  disappeared  after  a  few  cen- 
turies of  incomparable  lustre,  and  was  superseded 
by  Christianity,  for  which  it  had  in  some  measure 
prepared  a  lasting  triumph.  Religion  once  more 
took  as  its  directing  principle  the  care  of  souls,  and 
henceforth  assumed  the  role  of  the  faithful  guardian 
of  true  morality,  the  deadly  enemy  of  materialism 
and  atheism,  which  it  persistently  and  unfairly 
accused  of  corrupting  morals  and  of  destroying 


4  ETHICS,    METAPHYSICS,   AND    RELIGION. 

the  sense  of  duty  by  the  suppression  of  every 
sanction. 

Must  we  assume  that  the  moral  crisis  of  the 
present  day  will  end  in  the  same  manner?  Can 
philosophy  and  religion  help  us  now  as  they 
helped  the  ancient  world  ?  It  is  very  doubtful. 
In  the  first  place,  the  conditions  are  different. 
The  ancient  world  never  reached  a  state  of  social 
complexity  comparable  to  that  to  which  we 
have  been  brought  by  the  political  and  economical 
progress  of  the  century  which  has  just  drawn  to  a 
close;  most  of  the  problems  which  we  have  to 
solve  are  entirely  new.  Slavery,  the  condition  of 
woman  in  Greece  and  Rome,  the  absence  of  power- 
ful machinery  and  vast  industrial  centres,  the  lack 
of  consideration  paid  to  human  dignity,  the  inade- 
quate development  of  scientific  ideas  and  humani- 
tarian tendencies, — all  these  made  the  solution  of 
the  moral  problem  a  much  easier  task  than  it  is  at 
present. 

What,  in  fact,  is  Stoicism,  but  a  doctrine  of 
tension  due  to  reaction  against  a  general  relaxation 
of  morals  and  a  general  weakening  of  the  will  ? 
Epicureanism,  on  the  other  hand,  is  purely  a 
doctrine  of  apathy  springing  directly  from  dis- 
couragement, from  the  absence  of  conviction,  a 
doctrine  which  laid  desolate  the  Greek  world  at 
the  very  moment  when  Pyrrhonism  was  endeavour- 
ing, if  not  actually  to  destroy  action,  at  least  to 
deprive  it  of  every  motive.  The  spirit  of  the 
civilised  world  had  then  passed  that  celebrated 
stage  at  which  speculations,  however  bold,  did  not 
disturb  the  equilibrium  of  the  mental  or  of  the  moral 
faculties;  in  which  a  Plato  or  an  Aristotle  could 


MORAL   PHILOSOPHY.  5 

safely  propose  to  mankind  an  unrealisable  ideal,  too 
confident  in  the  wisdom  of  their  contemporaries  to 
fear  that  they  were  diverging  from  the  golden  mean. 
On  every  side  was  heard  the  eager  question — What 
shall  we  do  ?  And  with  equal  eagerness  men  adopted 
the  simple  solutions  within  the  grasp  of  the  ordinary 
intellect — avoid  action,  endure  suffering,  resist  evil, 
— solutions  which  were  rather  inspired  by  the  cir- 
cumstances of  the  case  than  by  the  genius  of  an 
individual. 

Stoicism  and  Epicureanism1  have  not  been  popular 
and  have  had  no  effect  on  morals,  because  the  two 
corresponding  moral  theories  were  the  immediate 
outcome  of  the  social  state  at  a  period  of  decadence. 
Their  success  is  to  be  explained  rather  by  socio- 
logical considerations  than  by  an  examination  of 
their  respective  values,  and  in  particular  of  their 
value  from  the  philosophical  point  of  view. 

3.  Moral  Philosophy. 

It  is  further  noticeable  that  philosophy  up  to  the 
present  time  has  not  been  prone  to  determine  men 
to  action  ;  it  has  remained  rather  speculative  than 
practical,  whether  it  has  an  a  priori  foundation  or 
the  scientific  basis  which  is  usually  attributed  to  it. — 
The  morality  taught  by  most  philosophers  is  gene- 
rally a  series  of  deductions  based  on  metaphysical 
principles.  These  principles  have  a  value  that  is 
entirely  subjective ;  it  is  readily  seen  that  they  vary 
with  each  school  of  thought,  that  they  are  in  mutual 
conflict,  and  that  they  fall  into  discredit,  being  the 

1  Cf.  Guyau,  La  Morale  a" Epicure,  p.  186 :  "  Epicureanism  had  a 
success  and  excited  in  its  disciples  an  enthusiasm  of  which  no  modern 
doctrine  can  give  the  slightest  idea." — TR. 


6  ETHICS,   METAPHYSICS,   AND   RELIGION. 

subject  of  unceasing  controversy.  Their  basis,  if 
empirical,  is  unsound,  because  of  the  limited  number 
of  facts  observed,  and  we  can  then  confront  them 
with  principles  for  which  with  equal  weight  an 
equally  incomplete  experience  claims  sanction.  Be- 
sides, the  ordinary  mind  cannot  revert  to  those  very 
general  principles  which  the  philosopher  reaches  by 
means  of  subtle  analysis,  and  which  alone  give  value 
to  deductions  and  precepts.  Finally,  a  philosophical 
system  is  generally  too  adventitious  a  part  of  the 
social  future  for  the  morality  which  is  therewith  con- 
nected to  have  any  influence  on  long-established 
morals,  or  on  minds  confused  by  the  disorder  of 
social  forces.  Karl  Marx  was  therefore  right  when 
he  spoke  of  the  "  Poverty  of  Philosophy  "  and  of  its 
powerlessness,  either  to  prevent  or  to  remedy  moral 
crises. 

4.  Powerlessness  oj  Philosophy. 

M.  Fouillee  considers1  that,  just  as  it  was  said  to 
the  poets — "  Shame  on  the  men  who  can  sing  while 
Rome  is  burning,"  so  under  the  present  circum- 
stances we  should  "tell  the  philosophers  that  they 
ought  not  to  be  content  with  speculation  when 
questions  of  life  and  death  are  in  the  air."  But  what 
can  philosophers  do,  if  they  are  reduced  to  a  general 
knowledge  of  the  world,  and  deal  with  a  hasty  and 
provisional  systematisation  of  hypotheses  laid  down 
by  experts  in  every  branch  of  science  ?  The  general 
philosophy  of  science  plays  a  more  and  more  limited 
part,  and  that  part  is  to  constantly  endeavour  to 
realise  the  unity  of  knowledge  by  co-ordinating  data 
of  which  we  feel  assured,  and  hypotheses  which  do 

1  La  France  au  Point  de  Vue  morale. 


POWERLESSNESS   OF*   PHILOSOPHY.  ? 

not  conflict  with  these  data.  This  cosmological 
work  affects  action  but  little,  but  it  is  perhaps  worth 
a  man's  while  to  realise  with  increasing  accuracy  his 
place  in  the  universe,  to  experience  a  sense  of 
modesty  when  his  own  insignificance  is  brought 
home  to  him,  and  a  sense  of  legitimate  pride  when 
he  appreciates  the  part  his  race  has  played  in  the 
course  of  universal  evolution.  But  that  lays  down 
for  him  no  well-defined  line  of  conduct,  and  we  may 
well  be  amused  to  see  philosophers  deducing  from  a 
few  vague  cosmological  premisses  an  equally  vague 
formula  of  duty,  compelled  as  they  are  to  further 
the  future  of  the  race,  to  develop  to  the  utmost  the 
psychic  forces,  and  to  secure  their  triumph  over 
the  unconscious  energies  at  work  in  the  universe.1 
If  all  philosophy  must  issue  in  morality,  according  to 
the  paraphrase  of  the  fundamental  axiom  of  dualistic 
spiritualism,  it  is  certainly  unnecessary  to  speculate 
with  so  much  heat. 

Apart  from  rational  cosmology,  theology  cannot 
teach  us  our  duty,  for  if  it  were  to  expound  to  us  the 
sovereign  will,  it  would  be  compelled  to  presuppose 
morality,  in  order  to  secure  its  right  to  represent  it 
as  the  supreme  rule  for  human  will ;  and  as  its  God 
would  have  to  be  the  moral  Ideal,  it  could  only  be 
conceived  in  accordance  with  a  moral  theory.  Of  all 
the  philosophical  movements  of  the  last  century  the 
most  important,  if  we  measure  importance  by  the 
effect  produced  on  the  ordinary  mind,  has  certainly 
been  evolutionism.  What  influence  has  it  had  on  public 
morality?  The  interest  it  aroused  was  mainly  due 
to  the  hostility  of  the  clergy,  both  Catholic  and 

1  This  formula  is  due  to  Rudolf  Muller  in  his  Naltirwissenschaftliche 
Seelenforschung)  vol.  ix.  pp.  585  et  seq. 


8  ETHICS,    METAPHYSICS,   AND   RELIGION. 

Protestant  ;l  it  very  soon  assumed  the  character  of 
bold  negation,  with  respect  to  the  morality  of 
theology  and  of  religious  belief;  but  this  agitation 
was  futile  from  the  practical  point  of  view — nothing 
was  gained  by  bringing  home  the  cause  of  moral 
unity  only  to  the  upright  conscience  and  the  en- 
lightened mind. 

5.  Powerlessness  of  Religion. 

If  philosophy  appears  to  be  completely  powerless, 
may  we  at  least  believe  that  a  great  religious  move- 
ment would  succeed  in  remedying  moral  anarchy? 
Contrary  to  Spencer's  view,  religion  appears  from  its 
origin  to  have  been  intimately  associated  with  the 
moral  development  of  humanity.  M.  Durkheim2 
even  considers  that  all  other  social  phenomena 
(morality  included)  have  issued  by  way  of  dissociation 
from  the  religious  phenomenon;  the  relationship 
began  by  being  an  essentially  religious  bond.  At 
most  we  can  ask  ourselves  if  economic  organisation 
is  an  exception,  and  is  derived  from  another  source. 
"  M.  Belot 3  thinks  that  religion  in  its  early  stages 
contained  morality,  not  like  living  matter  which  con- 
tains forms  which  may  afterwards  be  revealed,"  but 
"  like  a  shell  which  protects  the  embryo,  and  which 
covers  and  conceals  to  a  very  large  extent  the  spon- 
taneous work  of  which  almost  all  life  consists." 
However  this  point  of  detail  may  be  decided,  it  is 
difficult  even  to  some  of  our  contemporaries  to  com- 

1  White's  History  of  the  Conflict  between  Science  and  Religion. 

'2  Ann'ee  sociologique  (2nd  year,  1897-98),  "Definition  des  Pheno- 
menes  religieux." 

3  "La  Religion  comme  Principe  sociologique,"  Revue  philoso- 
phique,  March  1900,  p.  290. 


POWERLESSNESS  OF   RELIGION.  9 

pletely  separate  ethical  from  religious  idealism,  so  inti- 
mate has  their  union  been  for  many  generations. 

However,  M.  Fouillee  shows,  by  invoking  the  testi- 
mony of  eminent  Catholics  such  as  MM.  d'Hulst, 
Guibert,  and  Cardinal  Bourret,  that  religious  prac- 
tices become  more  and  more  capable  of  association 
with  a  fundamental  immorality.  It  seems  that  a 
religious  crisis  due  to  the  decay  of  religious  senti- 
ments has  followed  almost  every  stage  of  the  moral 
crisis.  This  is  the  inverse  of  what  was  occasionally 
maintained  when  religious  feeling  was  made  the 
condition  of  morality;  the  latter  would  rather  con- 
dition the  former. 

Doubtless  there  are  stages  in  every  social  evolution 
in  which  theological  dogma  presides  over  the  educa- 
tion of  youth,  in  which  priests  fashion  at  their  will 
the  intellect  and  the  heart ;  but  a  sacerdotal  body  is 
only  powerful,  that  is  to  say,  really  powerful,  so  long 
as  it  is  subject  to  the  influence  of  existing  morals 
and  of  the  ethical  current.  This  the  writers  above 
mentioned  express  very  clearly,  when  they  attribute 
the  decreasing  influence  of  the  clergy  on  public 
morality  to  their  remoteness  from  the  concerns  of 
everyday  life,  to  their  intellectual  inertia,  and  to 
their  ignorance  of  the  general  tendencies  of  modern 
society. 

We  cannot,  therefore,  count  on  religion,  so  called, 
to  put  an  end  to  the  moral  crisis;  religion  only 
influences  those  minds  which  are  in  need  of  belief, 
and  to  whom  a  prophet  or  a  saint  brings  the  faith 
for  which  they  crave. 

The  rapid  propagation  of  Christianity  is  explained 
from  a  purely  sociological1  point  of  view  by  the 

1  I.e.,  leaving  out  of  account  the  belief  in  the  Divinity  of  Christ, 


10  ETHICS,   METAPHYSICS,   AND   RELIGION. 

aspirations  of  a  throng  of  freedmen  and  slaves,  who 
welcomed  it  enthusiastically  because  they  craved 
pity,  love,  and  fraternity.  The  preaching  of  Moham- 
med responded  in  a  similar  manner  to  the  mystical 
and  warlike  tendencies  of  the  Arab  tribes,  the 
ethnical  character  of  which  assures  the  persistence  of 
Islamism.  But  among  the  more  intelligent  and  more 
educated  peoples  of  the  white  race,  that  similarity  of 
sentiments  and  tendencies  which  favours  great  reli- 
gious movements  could  not  persist.  The  era  of  great 
enthusiasm  seems  closed,  at  any  rate  to  our  European 
civilisation.  That  is  why  we  appeal  l  to  the  clergy  of 
the  different  denominations  to  aid  religious  faith  by 
the  help  of  psychology  and  sociology.  It  is  now 
obvious  that  the  sharpness  of  the  moral  crisis  cannot 
be  diminished  by  philosophy  alone,  nor  by  religion 
alone,  nor  by  philosophy  and  religion  combined— 
for  what  assistance  can  one  bring  to  the  other  ? 
It  may  be  that  ethical  religion  contributes  from 
the  very  loftiness  of  its  morality  to  the  realisation  of 
the  most  complete  possible  moral  unity  in  humanity; 
but  its  work  ought  to  be  preceded  in  every  case  by 
that  of  the  thinkers  and  the  savants,  who,  after 
having  learned  to  look  on  man  both  as  a  psycholo- 
gical and  as  a  social  being,  would  endeavour  to 
agree  on  the  first  principles  of  human  conduct. 

6.  Conditions  of  Morality. 

Sometimes  it  is  only  by  social  action  exercised  on 
every  class  of  society  and  individual  that  moral  work 
can  be  accomplished,  and  that  crisis  met  which  is 

1  M.  Fouillee,  for  example,    in   his   recent   volume,  La  France  au 
Point  de.  Vue  morale. 


CONDITIONS  OF  MORALITY.  II 

due  to  the  divergence  of  individual  views.  Now  dog- 
matism, under  whatever  form  it  presents  itself,  cannot 
be  an  acceptable  remedy.  Truth  is  not  imposed  by 
brute  force;  it  is  proposed  by  some,  accepted  by 
others,  and  becomes  common  thought  by  the  free 
adhesion  of  minds.  Everything  that  enters  into 
belief  by  pathological  suggestion,  in  consequence  of 
a  morbid  receptivity  of  the  intellect,  may  be  expelled 
in  the  same  way  in  which  it  wras  introduced.  The 
ethics  taught  by  a  master  will  only  become  the  real 
morality  of  the  race  if  it  is  discussed,  criticised,  and 
admitted  by  reason,  and  never  from  sheer  weakness 
of  will  or  mental  indolence. 

Hence,  every  man  must  make  his  own  morality, 
and  must  be  therefore  rendered  capable  of  making 
it  for  himself;  he  must  be  enlightened,  guided, 
advised,  and  placed  in  a  position  to  judge,  so  that 
theory  may  determine  a  practice  which  suits  him. 
Then,  either  there  will  be  an  inevitable  divergence, 
and  we  shall  have  to  give  up  moral  unity  and 
submit  to  an  indefinite  prolongation  of  the  present 
crisis,  or  an  agreement  will  take  place  which  will 
at  any  rate  put  an  end  to  dissensions  on  essential 
points. 

Now  the  primary  characteristic  of  science  is  that 
it  brings  minds  into  agreement  by  furnishing  them 
with  universal  and  necessary  principles.  We  may 
therefore  hope  that  moral  unity  will  be  realised  if 
ethics  can  be  based  on  science  in  general,  or  on  one 
of  the  sciences  in  particular. 


12  SCIENTIFIC  MORALITY. 

II. 

SCIENTIFIC   MORALITY. 

7.  Independent  Ethics. 

Scientific  psychology  has  been  reproached  with 
being  soulless;  this  reproach  is  really  praise,  for  a 
metaphysical  theory  of  the  soul,  whether  materialistic 
or  spiritualistic,  realistic  or  idealistic,  can  only  viti- 
ate any  scientific  investigation  into  the  nature  of 
phenomena.  In  the  same  manner,  to  accuse  scienti- 
fic morality  of  being  a  practical  doctrine  without 
theology  or  preliminary  metaphysics  is  also  praise. 

No  doubt  every  scientific  application  assumes 
certain  philosophic  postulates  which  criticism  has 
readily  discovered:  for  instance,  that  there  are  laws 
of  nature;  that  the  principle  of  causality  is  of 
universal  value,  and  of  necessary  application  to 
phenomena,  etc.  This  is  used  to  prove — poor 
victory — that  every  philosopher  and  moralist  alike 
does  the  same  without  hesitation,  so  that  neither 
science  nor  ethics  is  independent  of  philosophic 
criticism. 

This  assertion  of  the  rights  of  philosophy  is  per- 
fectly legitimate.  There  are  philosophic  truths,  the 
most  general  of  all,  which  have  such  an  objectivity 
that  one  runs  no  risk  in  admitting  them.  Empiricism 
and  rationalism,  realism  and  idealism,  only  come 
into  actual  conflict  in  the  region  of  unverifiable 
hypotheses;  and  science  and  ethics  need  not  follow 
philosophy  into  this  region. 

The  independence  which  is  claimed  by  ethics  is  not 


THE    SCIENCE    OF   ETHICS.  13 

independence  with  respect  to  philosophic  criticism; 
most  contemporary  thinkers  consider,  with  Kant, 
that  nothing  can  escape  criticism,  ethics  no  more 
than  religion  or  science.  But  the  right  that  is 
accorded  to  criticism  to  push  its  investigations  as 
far  as  possible  into  the  first  principles  of  every 
science  or  every  theory,  into  their  nature,  and  even 
into  their  value,  does  not  go  so  far  as  to  justify  the 
making  of  ethics  a  mere  dependency  of  philosophy. 

8.  The  Science  of  Ethics. 

M.  Renouvier  has  not  hesitated  to  write  "of  the 
science  of  ethics  as  a  science  which  is  at  first  a  pure 
science  and  subsequently  an  applied  science,-  under 
the  name  of  the  principles  of  law."1  He  has  even 
compared  this  new  science  to  mathematics,  the 
simplicity  and  rigour  of  which  science  seem,  how- 
ever, but  ill  adapted  to  favour  such  a  comparison. 
"  Mathematics  and  ethics  have  this  much  in 
common,  if  they  claim  to  be  sciences  they  must 
be  based  on  pure  concepts.  Experience  and  history 
are  further  from  representing  the  laws  of  ethics  than 
nature  is  from  the  accurate  realisation  of  mathe- 
matical ideas;  but  these  laws  and  ideas  are  rational 
forms  equally  necessary,  the  one  to  be  the  rule  of  the 
senses,  and  the  other  to  guide  and  form  a  judgment 
on  life."2  But  this  science  which  is  so  near  to  the 
scientific  ideal  must  be  based  on  a  philosophic  doc- 
trine, "  for  nothing  can  overthrow  one  doctrine  but 
another  doctrine;  there  is  a  philosophy,  and  one 
alone,  which  satisfies  this  condition  of  being,  a 

1  Ch.  Renouvier,  Science  de  la  Morale^  Paris  (Ladrange),  1869. 

2  Renouvier,  op.  cit.,  Preface. 


14  SCIENTIFIC    MORALITY. 

doctrine  which  is  distinct  from  the  rest,  and  that 
is  critical  philosophy,  .  .  .  because  it  is  itself,  in  so 
far  as  it  examines,  or  criticises,  or  analyses  represen- 
tations, either  a  science  already,  or  the  beginning  of 
science  in  every  question  which  is  a  subject  of  con- 
troversy among  philosophers." 

It  is  to  be  feared  that  M.  Renouvier  exaggerates 
the  need  of  critical  philosophy  to  a  science  which  finds 
in  experience  and  in  history  those  approximations, 
the  rectification  or  completion  of  wrhich  would  provide 
us  with  perfect  types  of  moral  actions,  and  which  at 
the  same  time  are  sufficient  to  draw  up  the  data  of 
experience  and  to  translate  them  into  perfect  geo- 
metrical forms.  Ethics  is  in  much  more  urgent 
need^-and  M.  Renouvier  himself  explicitly  admits  it— 
of  the  methodic  study  of  psychological  and  socio- 
logical facts  both  present  and  past. 

9.  Kantian  Ethics  and  its  Postulates. 

Is  not  the  "  critical  philosophy "  of  which  M. 
Renouvier  speaks  almost  identical  with  the  philo- 
sophy of  Kant,  modified  no  doubt  as  far  as  belief  in 
the  noumenon  is  concerned,  but  kept  intact  by  the 
neo-criticists  as  far  as  it  affects  practical  reason  ? 

Now  Kant,  no  doubt,  had  the  merit  of  taking  duty 
as  his  point  of  departure,  a  "rational  fact";  that  is 
to  say  of  such  a  universality  as  cannot  be  misunder- 
stood, and  as  is  imposed  on  all  adult  and  reflective 
minds.  As  M.  Dugas1  has  remarked,  the  idea  of 
duty  is  common  to  all  moral  doctrine,  although  it 
has  not  always  been  distinguished  from  the  less 
abstract  conceptions  which  envelop  it.  "  It  is  not 

1  Revue  philosophique^  1897,  t.  xliv.  p.  390. 


KANTIAN    ETHICS    AND    ITS    POSTULATES.  15 

foreign  to  hedonistic  morality,  and  it  is  essential  to 
utilitarian  ethics,  even  when  reduced  to  egoism." 
Naturalistic  morality  has  closely  connected  it  with 
this  moral  sentiment  which,  as  Darwin  says,  "we 
define  by  saying  it  must  be  obeyed."  In  every  theory 
\vhich  distinguishes  the  moral  good  from  every  other 
good  it  is  this  which  must  be  acquired  or  realised. 
Kant  was  therefore  right  in  devoting  himself  to 
researches  which  expose  him  to  the  charge  of  "  for- 
malism," but  none  the  less  remain  a  valuable  example 
of  philosophical  analysis. 

But  after  having  made  ethics  the  doctrine  of 
obligation,  has  he  in  the  sequel  safeguarded  in- 
dependence ?  Have  not  metaphysical  and  theological 
ideas  affected  deductions  which  are  apparently  rigorous 
and  impartial  ? 

The  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  already  shows  that 
Kant  had  a  keen  desire  to  restore  belief  in  God, 
in  the  immortality  of  the  soul,  and  in  liberty — a 
belief  which  was  destroyed  by  the  disputes  of  philo- 
sophers, and  which  could  not  be  established  save 
upon  new  foundations. 

Further,  Kant  also  proceeds  to  make  of  liberty, 
which  is  unintelligible  to  us  because  it  exists  in  "  the 
intelligible  world,"  the  ratio  essendi  of  duty;  of  future 
sanction,  the  consequence  of  moral  obligation;  and 
of  the  existence  of  God,  the  consequence  of  sanction 
beyond  the  tomb.  Hence  it  seems  that  morality  has 
for  its  sole  aim  the  restoration  of  the  idols  which 
criticism  destroys.  Not  only  is  ethics  thus  taken  as 
the  means,  not  only  does  it  cease  to  be  a  real  aim, 
but  it  is  also  placed  in  relative  opposition  to  the 
criticism  on  which  we  profess  to  base  it.  It  is  as 
much  the  slave  of  metaphysics  and  theology  as  ever. 


l6  SCIENTIFIC   MORALITY. 

But  now  its  servitude  is  more  disguised,  and  is  even 
veiled  under  the  form  of  supremacy. 

10.  Science  and  Ethics. 

We  must,  on  the  contrary,  have  a  morality  estab- 
lished as  science  is,  without  preconceived  ideas, 
without  prejudice,  without  the  secret  intention  of 
issuing  in  the  justification  of  an  opinion,  be  it  meta- 
physical, or  religious,  or  political.  The  moralist,  like 
the  savant,  must  at  the  beginning  of  his  investiga- 
tions be  ignorant  of  the  point  at  which  he  will 
emerge,  and  must  therefore  be  a  man  of  no  particular 
school. 

But  can  he  do  what  may  be  fairly  called  scientific 
work  ?  M.  Durkheim1  admits  with  M.  Renouvier  the 
possibility  of  constructing  "a  science  of  ethics." 
The  moralists,  he  says,  "  who  deduce  their  doctrine 
not  from  an  a  priori  principle,  but  from  certain  pro- 
positions borrowed  from  one  or  more  positive  sciences, 
qualify  their  scientific  morality."  2 

Our  aim  is  not  to  deduce  ethics  from  science,  but 
to  construct  the  science  of  ethics,  which  is  quite  a 
different  matter.  For  that  purpose  M.  Durkheim 
"  undertakes  to  determine  the  reasons  of  an  experi- 
mental order  on  which  morality  is  formed,  trans- 
formed, and  maintained,"  to  study  the  rules  of  action 

1  La  Division  dti  Travail  social,  Preface.     Paris,  Alcan,  1893. 

2  The  term  "scientific  "  has  been  sometimes  quite  wrongly  applied 
to  certain  moral  doctrines  by  intellects  even  as  keen  as  that  of  M.  Bout- 
roux,  who  seems  to  believe  that  scientific  morality  is  compelled  to  follow 
the  lines  of  the  natural  sciences,  and  therefore  must  in  these  days  be 
informed  by  the  transformist,  evolutionist,  and  even  the  materialistic 
spirit.     It  is  scarcely  necessary  to  point  out  the  abuse  of  terms  which 
leads  one  to  qualify  as  scientific  that  morality  which  is  connected  with  a 
scientific  hypothesis  of  indefinite  value. 


THE  REAL  AND  THE  IDEAL,         IJ 

laid  down  for  the  individual  by  collectivity,  as  well  as 
by  all  the  other  facts  of  social  constraint  which  have 
given  birth  to  the  morals  of  different  epochs  and  of 
different  countries. 

M.  Durkheim  would  scout  the  idle  objection  that 
science  only  studies  what  is  or  has  been.  The  scientific 
knowledge  of  what  is  or  has  been  may  well  give  an 
idea  of  what  will  be,  but  not  of  what  ought  to  be,  should 
be,  or  would  have  been.  Science,  says  the  sociologist, 
"  can  help  us  to  find  the  direction  in  which  we  should 
orientate  our  conduct,  and  to  determine  the  ideal 
towards  which  we  are  but  blindly  groping.  Only, 
we  cannot  raise  ourselves  to  that  ideal  until  we  have 
observed  the  real  and  extricated  ourselves  from  it. 
But  is  it  possible  to  proceed  in  any  other  way  ? 
Even  the  most  intemperate  idealists  cannot  follow 
any  other  method,  for  the  ideal  rests  on  nothing  if 
it  is  not  rooted  in  reality."  l 

ii.  The  Real  and  the  Ideal. 

It  seems  that  M.  Durkheim  and  M.  Renouvier  are 
fundamentally  agreed  that  the  real  needs  rectification, 
and  that  rectification  is  possible.  It  is  true  that  the 
latter  expects  it  from  pure  reason,  by  an  operation 
analogous  to  that  by  which  mathematics  is  consti- 
tuted, while  the  former  counts  on  a  kind  of  induction 
founded  on  experience,  thanks  to  which  we  can 
establish  a  law  of  social  evolution,  a  social  type 
which  may  be  realised.  "  The  objective  that  science 
offers  to  the  will "  is  a  "  normal  type  entirely  in 
agreement  with  itself,  which  has  eliminated  or 
redressed  the  contradictions,  that  is  to  say,  the 

1  Durkheim,  op.  cit.,  p.  4. 

2 


l8  SCIENTIFIC   MORALITY, 

imperfections,  which  it  contained."  M.  Durkheim 
therefore  gives  to  sociology  a  role  which  M.  Renouvier 
refuses  to  it,  and  it  cannot  be  denied  that  the  former 
has  the  true  scientific  spirit  which,  in  proportion  as 
the  fact  to  be  studied  becomes  more  and  more  complex, 
awards  a  wider  role  to  observation,  to  experiment, 
and  to  induction. 

But  wide  as  may  be  the  role  that  is  given  by 
M.  Durkheim  to  social  science,  the  latter  cannot  be 
confused  writh  ethics.  If  social  science  were  ethics, 
it  could  only  "  make  of  us  spectators  indifferent  or 
resigned  to  reality,".1  forcing  itself  with  the  Stoic  sage 
to  learn  the  natural  law  in  order  to  have  further 
knowledge  of  wrhat  it  reserves  to  us,  whither  it  leads 
us,  and  whither,  in  the  words  of  Cleanthes,2  it  would 
lead  us  if,  in  a  frenzy  at  its  restrictions,  we  should 
refuse  to  observe  it  and  to  follow  it. 

"  If  we  know  in  what  direction  the  evolution  of 
the  right  of  property  is  taking  place  as  societies  be- 
come more  voluminous  and  dense,  and  if  some  fresh 
increase  of  volume  and  density  necessitates  fresh 
modifications,  we  can  foresee  them,  and  foreseeing 
them  we  can  will  them  in  advance."  This  is  the  Stoic 
morality,  consisting  solely  in  the  pursuit  of  nature, 
in  "  life  in  conformity  with  the  natural  law,"  which 
sociology  reveals  to  us  as  rigidly  as  a  law  in  physics 
or  astronomy;  but  we  are  as  little  content  with  that 
as  is  M.  Durkheim. 

Thus  some  knowledge  of  a  higher  order  than 
social  science  must  regulate  our  conduct  under 
certain  circumstances,  in  which  it  is  not  enough  to 

1  Id,y  ibid.,  p.  v. 

2  Hymn  to  Zeus  (attributed   to   Cleanthes,  the  head  of  the  Stoics 
between  Zeno  and  Chrysippus). — TR. 


THE   TECHNICAL   CHARACTER   OF   MORALITY.       IQ 

be  the  passive  spectator  of  natural  evolution.     Dare 
we  assert  that  this  will  be  a  real  science  ? 


12.  The  Technical  Character  of  Morality. 

It  must  be  recognised  that  science  cannot  issue 
from  necessity;  it  does  not  closely  embrace  reality, 
nor  does  it  embrace  it  entirely;  everything  that  is 
contingent  or  accidental,  everything  which  depends 
on  individual  variations,  escapes  it.  Its  domain  is 
that  of  abstractions.  The  domain  of  morality  is  the 
field  of  human  actions  in  which  are  evolved  concrete 
beings  and  complex  personalities  incessantly  in  pro- 
cess of  evolution,  integration,  and  disintegration. 

That  is  why  the  difference  which  exists  between 
moral  and  physical  laws  has  been  for  a  long  time 
rightly  pointed  out.  The  latter  are  inviolable  ;  their 
necessity  is  such  that  no  one  can  elude  their  effects ; 
the  former,  on  the  contrary,  are  easily  eluded ;  they 
may  be  either  obeyed  or  violated.  They  are,  there- 
fore, not  really  laws,  if  it  is  wise  to  restrict  that 
name  to  the  necessary  relations  established  between 
two  orders  of  facts,  each  represented  by  an  abstract 
term  (which  does  not  correspond  more  exactly  to 
any  particular  fact).  The  so-called  moral  laws  are 
precepts — prescriptions  analogous  to  the  prudent 
counsel  that  a  father  gives  his  son,  or  to  the  tech- 
nical rules  that  a  workman  teaches  his  apprentice. 

The  peculiar  characteristic  of  morality  springs 
from  a  different  class  of  considerations. 

The  normal  being  is  not  an  unchangeable  ideal ; 
what  is  normal  at  a  given  time  for  a  certain  race 
or  at  a  certain  stage  of  civilisation  is  not  so  under 
other  circumstances.  We,  being  men  of  a  certain 


20  SCIENTIFIC   MORALITY. 

epoch  and  of  a  determined  environment,  can  only 
conceive  an  ideal  relative  to  ourselves,  to  our  mental 
structure,  to  our  morals,  and  to  our  essential  tend- 
encies. It  is  sufficient  to  consider  the  evolution  of 
mind  in  the  few  centuries  which  separate  us  from 
ancient  Greece,  to  see  how  modified,  for  instance, 
are  conceptions  as  to  the  social  role  of  women 
and  even  the  morals  of  women,  or  indeed  the 
fundamental  notions  either  of  public  law  or  of  the 
family. 

We  shall,  therefore,  never  elaborate  a  morality  of 
value  to  any  but  a  given  civilisation  and  a  few 
human  generations — a  morality  which  will  be  im- 
posed upon  men's  minds  only  for  a  length  of  time, 
which  may  be  long  as  far  as  we  are  concerned,  but 
very  short  with  reference  to  human  evolution  taken 
as  a  whole. 

If  we  can  give  up  the  idea  of  proposing  as  a  model 
to  the  man  of  to-day  a  type  that  is  to  be  of  value  at 
N  all  times  and  places,  a  type  that  is,  therefore,  ab- 
stract and  without  influence  over  the  will  or  over 
morals,  we  must  force  ourselves  to  conceive  that  type 
which  is  in  closest  conformity  with  the  indications  of 
sociology.  But  between  this  ideal  and  the  scientific 
data  which  are  nearest  to  concrete  conceptions, 
there  is  still  a  considerable  gap.  How  can  we  fill 
that  gap  ?  Experience  shows  us  imperfect  types, 
systems  incompletely  realised,  and  tendencies  more 
or  less  divergent.  Pure  scientific  prevision  consists 
in  the  application  to  the  future  of  laws  which  are 
recognised  as  applicable  to  the  facts  of  the  past ;  it 
does  not,  therefore,  pass  beyond  the  scope  of  the 
facts  laid  down  by  experience.  But  it  can  pass 
beyond  by  the  aid  of  what  is  called  "sociological 


THE  TECHNICAL  CHARACTER  OF  MORALITY.   21 

prevision,"  which  is  rather  a  part  of  "  social  philo- 
sophy "  than  of  social  science,  for  it  is  composed  of 
more  or  less  probable  hypotheses;  it  is  a  kind  of 
prediction  well  founded  and  based  on  science. 

The  interpretation  of  sociological  data  is  already 
giving  rise  to  certain  variations.  Further,  the  ideal 
conceived  in  conformity  with  sociological  prevision 
does  not  impose  itself  with  sufficient  rigour  on  all 
minds  for  us  to  be  able  to  conceive  without  absurdity 
of  another  ideal,  different,  if  not  in  its  essential 
features,  at  least  in  its  details. 

As  a  matter  of  fact,  do  we  not  often  meet  with 
men  who  appreciate  with  great  justice  of  view  the 
social  type  which  the  majority  of  their  fellow-citizens 
tend  to  realise — a  realisation  as  regular  as  it  is  un- 
conscious— and  yet  who  affirm  that  it  is  their  duty, 
and  that  it  would  be  the  duty  of  all  of  us,  to  re-act 
against  the  general  tendency,  to  prevent  the  realisa- 
tion of  this  type,  and  to  \vork  for  the  realisation 
of  another  slightly  different  but  still  to  them  a 
realisable  type  ? 

Would  these  people  be  better  informed,  better 
provided  with  full  scientific  information,  would  they 
be  more  apt  to  display  foresight,  if  they  did  not  cease 
to  oppose  their  ideal  to  the  reality  which  is  in  the 
process  of  making,  and  to  condemn  what  exists  by 
comparing  it  with  what,  in  their  opinion,  ought  to 
exist  ?  All  other  men  could  give  way  to  the  pressure 
of  collectivity,  to  the  constraint  exercised  by  the 
multitude,  to  the  apparent  necessity  of  the  social 
future,  while  these  "idealists,"  rebelling  against 
imitation  and  fashion,  opposing  custom  and  received 
opinion,  would  none  the  less  persist  in  exalting  their 
own  conception,  and  in  encouraging  their  fellows  to 


22  SCIENTIFIC    MORALITY. 

follow   them   in   what   they  would   call   "  the   good 
way." 

Is  such  an  idealism  to  be  condemned  ?  is  it  con- 
trary to  the  conception  of  a  really  scientific 
morality  ?  And  the  naturalistic  thesis  sustained  by 
those  who  claim  that  man  ought  to  live  according  to 
his  nature,  a  nature  perhaps  fundamentally  animal, 
ought  it  a  priori  to  have  our  preference  ?  If  hesita- 
tion is  permitted  in  the  choice  of  two  conflicting 
theses,  it  is  because  we  have  left  the  scientific 
domain.  We  have  entered  into  the  domain  of 
practice  and  of  art,  and  morals  is  rather  a  "  technical 
theory"  than  a  science.  It  is  precisely  because  we 
can  conceive  of  ethics  as  a  technical  theory,  that 
naturalism  and  idealism  can  be  reconciled. 

13.  Spiritualism,  Idealism,  and  Naturalism. 

In  the  first  place,  it  is  important  not  to  confuse 
idealism  and  spiritualism.  "The  spiritualistic  prin- 
ciple tends  to  a  negation  of  nature,"  says  M.  Darlu. 
"This  is  the  sign  by  which  the  filiation  of  spiri- 
tualistic ideas  can  be  recognised.  There  is  in  the 
soul  a  fixed  point,  spiritual  in  its  nature,  analogous 
to  divine  things,  as  Plato  was  so  fond  of  saying."1 

To  say  that  the  spirit  is  essentially  opposed  to 
nature  is  to  make  an  affirmation  without  proof, 
obviously  inspired  by  the  ancient  metaphysical 
theory  of  a  radical  distinction  between  matter  and 
mind,  between  soul  and  body,  between  life  and 
thought.  What  is  the  objective  value  of  this  theory, 
based,  no  doubt,  as  it  was,  on  common  beliefs  sug- 

1  La  Classification  des  Idees  morales  du  Temps  present,  1900,  pp. 
30-36.  Paris,  Alcan. 


SPIRITUALISM,    IDEALISM,    AND    NATURALISM.      23 

gested  by  the  sight  of  death  ?  So  far,  both  in  anti-, 
quity  and  in  our  own  times,  it  has  only  offered 
proofs  by  introducing  into  philosophic  speculation 
a  very  unsatisfactory  dualism,  by  increasing  the 
number  of  insoluble  problems,  and  by  compelling  a 
Descartes  to  place  this  mystery  at  the  very  beginning 
of  his  explanations. 

Nothing  has  ever  proved  the  distinction  and 
opposition  of  the  "extended"  and  the  "thinking" 
substance,  and  we  ask  ourselves  the  reason  of  the 
extraordinary  felicity  of  that  passage  in  the  Timczus,1 
in  which  Plato  represents  the  soul  as  depressed  and 
dragged  down,  on  entering  a  natural  body.  This 
purely  metaphysical  hypothesis  is  the  basis  of  all 
the  mystical  morality,  and  is  one  of  the  principal 
foundations  of  the  spiritualistic  morality;  the  fragi- 
lity of  the  foundation  betrays  the  weakness  of  the 
structure. 

But  idealism  is  strongly  opposed  to  dualistic 
spiritualism.  The  existence  of  psychic  phenomena 
amid  the  mechanical  psycho-chemical  and  biological 
phenomena,  which  constitute  the  rest  of  nature,  is 
completely  established,  as  well  as  the  existence  of 
necessary  relations  between  this  and  other  orders  of 
facts.  Experience  shows  us  in  the  "  phenomena 
of  the  soul,"  from  the  humblest  to  the  most  lofty, 
from  simple  sensation  to  the  most  audacious  specula- 
tion, the  elements  of  nature  and  the  factors  of  the 
cosmic  future;  it  does  not  allow  us  to  contrast  the 
ethics  of  the  mind  with  the  ethics  of  nature,  but  it 
invites  us  to  participate  more  and  more  in  universal 
evolution  by  the  means  with  which  we  have  been 

1  [?  41  et  seq.     In  some  respects  a  more  appropriate  reference  would 
have  been  to  the  Phaedo,  sect.  81.]— TR, 


24  SCIENTIFIC    MORALITY. 

provided  by  nature — by  prevision  and  imagination, 
and  by  the  power  of  the  idea.  To  the  idealist, 
everything  is  impregnated  with  thought.  Nature 
.  and  the  ideal,  far  from  being  mutually  exclusive,  are 
•  in  agreement — nature  tending  towards  an  ideal,  and 
the  ideal  that  we  can  conceive  being  necessarily  in 
the  extension  of  nature.  We  do  not  imagine  an 
ideal  for  the  purpose  of  mocking  at  the  real,  to  have 
the  right  of  despising  nature  and  of  avoiding  it  as 
much  as  possible,  but  rather  to  free  ourselves  from 
natural  necessity,  to  cease  to  be  spectators,  powerless 
and  resigned,  of  the  cosmic  evolution. 

The  knowledge  of  nature  can  only  explain  our 
conduct;  it  can  tell  us  why,  our  nature  and  nature 
in  general  being  such  as  they  are,  we  ought  to  act  in 
such  and  such  a  manner,  so  as  to  remain  in  agreement 
with  ourselves.  It  may  no  doubt  be  a  factor  in 
progress,  for  it  is  always  possible  to  bring  about 
more  systematisation  and  more  coherence  in  a  given 
type.  But  it  cannot  enable  us  to  evolve  new  types; 
it  cannot  lead  to  important  modifications;  it  cannot 
show  us  the  necessity  of  innovation  and  invention. 
Now,  invention  is  as  indispensable  in  ethical  as  it  is 
in  scientific  or  in  industrial  matter.  No  doubt  ethical 
invention  is  subject  to  the  same  psychological  and 
sociological  laws  as  industrial  invention :  the  human 
mind  cannot  be  independent  of  it ;  for  it  to  be  pro- 
ductive, the  mind  must  be  associated  with  anterior 
data  of  which  the  experience  of  reality  is  the  only 
source;  for  it  to  have  a  value  and  to  be  accepted  and 
fruitful,  it  must  answrer  to  a  need  and  to  a  powerful 
tendency,  and  it  must  be  the  extremity  of  a  line  of 
which  the  real  and  the  present  is  necessarily  the 
point  of  departure. 


MORALS    AS    A   TECHNICAL    PROCESS.  25 

14.  Morals  as  a  Technical  Process. 

Moral  invention  which  justifies  idealism,  like  other 
inventions,  cannot,  generally  speaking,  be  antici- 
pated.1 It  may  baffle  sociological  prevision;  it  may 
by  its  effects,  by  its  social  notoriety,  create  unex- 
pected modifications  to  which  conduct  must  be 
adapted.  Now,  adaptation  to  fluctuating  or  unex- 
pected conditions  calls  into  play  human  art  and 
human  industry.  Moral  activity  becomes  thereby  a 
very  complex  and  delicate  art,  wrhich  must  advance 
under  the  guidance  of  a  theory  approximating  as 
closely  as  possible  to  practice. 

Moral  theory  is  therefore  analogous  to  the  art  of 
the  doctor  or  the  carpenter.  The  scientific  know- 
ledge of  the  doctor  is  manifold,  drawn  from  various 
sciences,  connected  by  a  practical  design,  and  de- 
liberately combined  for  certain  ends.  Thus  the 
combination  is  of  a  different  type  to  the  disinterested 
and  methodic  character  of  science,  which  is  uncon- 
cerned with  any  practical  end.  So  it  is  with  the 
totality  of  scientific  knowledge,  which,  together 
with  certain  sociological  hypotheses  or  conjectures, 
constitutes  the  basis  of  the  moral  theory,  and  gives 
to  it  the  character  of  a  scientific  theory  without  its 
having  that  of  a  science  properly  so  called.  The 
more  arbitrary  is  the  conception  of  the  moral  ideal 
which  is  an  integral  part  of  this  theory,  the  more 
remote  we  are  from  rigour  and  objectivity,  and  the 
more  we  imperil  the  agreement  of  the  moral  con- 

1  Cf.  Guyau,  Esquisse  d^une  Morale  sans  Responsabilite  ni  Sanction, 
p.  30:  "  Even  the  acts  which  issue  in  complete  self-consciousness  have 
in  general  their  origin  in  blind  instincts  and  reflex  movements."  As 
we  shall  see  further  on,  this  is  true  both  of  the  conception  and  of  the 
choice  of  acts. 


26  INDIVIDUAL    AND    SOCIAL    ETHICS. 

science.  We  may  therefore  force  ourselves  to  reduce 
to  a  minimum  the  role  of  subjectivity  by  incessantly 
increasing  the  sum  of  scientific  knowledge;  we  must 
not  hope  to  annihilate  it. 

III. 
INDIVIDUAL  AND  SOCIAL  ETHICS. 

15.  The  Arts  and  Ethics. 

Although  ethics  is  a  theory  with  a  scientific  basis 
rather  than  a  science,  can  we  say  that  it  is  on  every 
point  analogous  to  the  theories  which  dominate  the 
art  of  the  doctor  or  the  carpenter,  or  which  direct 
the  activity  of  the  artisan  ?  Is  not  the  art  of  moral 
conduct  a  higher  art  ? 

Kant  asserted  that  he  had  established  a  profound 
distinction  between  ethics  and  other  technical 
theories,  by  showing  that  the  latter  furnish  "  hypo- 
thetic imperatives,"  and  the  former  a  "categoric 
imperative."  The  distinction  is  assuredly  correct.  A 
man  cannot  be  blamed  because  he  does  not  build  a 
house,  or  do  the  work  of  a  farmer  or  of  a  business 
man,  in  the  same  way  that  he  can  be  blamed  because 
he  is  dishonourable. 

But  the  difference  ought  never  to  be  exaggerated. 
The  doctor  who,  having  undertaken  the  care  of  a 
sick  man,  shows  lack  of  interest  or  skill,  will  rightly 
lose  in  moral  reputation  for  not  having  performed  his 
duty  as  well  as  he  could  have  performed  it  had  he 
been  more  skilled,  better  trained,  or  more  devoted  to 
his  patient.  That  is  because  in  even  the  lowest  of 
crafts — if  indeed  any  craft  is  low — once  an  end  pro- 


THE    ARTS   AND    ETHICS.  27 

posed  has  been  accepted  by  the  agent,  there  is  an  • 
obligation  to   respond  to  the  requirements  of  that 
end,  and  to  realise  completely  all  the  means  that  are 
best  assured  to  attain  that  end. 

It  may  be  that  the  first  of  these  obligations  is 
self-consistency,  not  to  be  self-contradictory,  and 
therefore  not  to  negate  one's  own  nature  as  a 
reasonable  being. 

The  idea  of  duty  is  therefore  closely  connected 
with  the  accomplishment  of  every  task.  A  man  is 
not  virtuous  only  at  certain  hours  of  the  day,  and 
under  certain  circumstances;  nothing  is  indifferent  to 
morality,  and  the  art  of  doing  one's  duty  is  step 
by  step  akin  to  the  art  of  following  one's  trade. 
Morality  also  penetrates  with  its  categoric  impera- 
tive every  hypothetical  imperative.  It  aspires  not 
only  to  lay  down  the  rules  of  universal  conduct 
imposed  on  all  men  under  all  circumstances,  but 
to  control  all  individual  modes  of  action.  And 
further,  by  seeking  the  realisation  of  an  ideal 
common  to  all  minds,  it  is  called  upon  to  sub- 
ordinate as  closely  as  possible  to  that  ideal 
all  private  ends,  to  subordinate  them  one  to 
another,  or  to  co-ordinate  them  in  a  vast  synthetic 
unity. 

We  are,  therefore,  unable  to  separate  the  art  of 
human  conduct  from  special  arts  such  as  those  of  the 
doctor  or  of  the  cobbler,  without  an  abstraction  which 
is  prejudicial  to  the  very  dignity  of  morals  and  to  a 
healthy  appreciation  of  its  scope.  It  is,  on  the  con- 
trary, far  better  to  bring  together  as  much  as  possible 
the  ethic  of  the  particular  technicalities  which  are 
most  dependent  on  science  for  assistance.  The 
architect  has  his  own  way  of  imagining  the  house 


28  INDIVIDUAL    AND    SOCIAL    ETHICS. 

he  intends  to  build,  just  as  the  baker  has  his  own 
method  of  determining  the  quality  of  the  bread  which 
he  intends  to  sell ;  but  the  house  must  still  respond 
to  the  general  needs  for  which  buildings  are  con- 
structed, and  to  the  particular  requirements  which 
have  determined  its  construction;  while  the  bread 
must  satisfy  the  taste  of  its  purchasers.  A  fortiori, 
the  doctor,  although  he  has  the  choice  between  many 
drugs,  and  between  the  various  methods  of  treatment 
which  are  suitable  to  the  case  of  his  patient,  sees  his 
choice  is  narrowly  limited  in  proportion  as  his  know- 
ledge of  the  temperament  of  his  patient  and  of  the 
causes  of  the  disease  become  more  complete.  One 
step  therefore  brings  us  to  ethics,  that  theory  of 
human  activity  which  is  suited  to  secure  not  only 

'  physiological,  but  psychological,  and,  above  all,  social 

•  health. 

As  an  intermediary,  we  find  hygiene,  the  laws  of 
which  are  sometimes  considered  as  moral  laws — 
for  instance,  when  moralists  advise  temperance, 
moderation  in  pleasure,  etc.  Moral  hygiene  is  in 
every  case  an  important  branch  of  ethics,  and  it 
is'  impossible  to  separate  it  from  the  hygiene  of  the 
body. 

Instead  of  simply  considering  the  needs  of  the 
organism,  as  in  the  case  of  medicine  and  ordinary 
hygiene,  ethics  takes  into  account  all  the  essential 
tendencies  of  man ;  and,  with  a  view  to  either 
strengthening  them  or  opposing  them,  the  accidental 
tendencies  of  the  men  of  a  particular  time  and  place. 
Its  object  is  therefore  much  more  complex  than  that 
of  medicine;  it  is  the  most  complex  of  all,  and 
the  most  interesting  because  it  embraces  the  whole 
concrete  being. 


SOCIAL   ETHICS.  2Q 

16.  Social  Ethics. 

Most  moralists  have  reduced  this  being  to  an 
abstraction,  to  man  himself.  They  have  taken  into 
account  neither  his  social  relations  nor  even  his  cor- 
poreal needs  and  appetites ;  they  have  acted  as  though 
he  were  a  "  naked  soul "  or  a  "  pure  intellect."  "  How- 
ever," as  M.  Boutroux  remarks,1  "  the  modern  spirit 
is  quite  determined  to  imprint  the  concrete  form  on 
ethics.  When  we  speak  of  duty  in  a  general  sense, 
of  country,  of  peace,  and  of  fraternity,  we  see  how 
readily  men  agree ;  differences  only  begin  when  they  • 
discuss  the  means  whereby  these  noble  ends  may  be- 
attained.  Our  life  is  very  complex,  and  the  number 
of  our  relations  is  daily  increasing.  We  want  a 
system  of  morality  which  enters  into  every  detail, 
which  does  not  merely  tell  us  that  we  must  do  good, 
but  in  what  that  good  consists.  .  .  .  To  the  ethics  of 
humanity  is  joined  that  of  the  particular  individual 
which  we  happen  to  be,  according  to  our  position  in 
the  world,  and  in  society."  "  We  must  not  forget," 
says  M.  Malapert,2  "that  beyond  the  individual  there 
is  the  social  group  and  the  human  race;  in  the  con- 
ception of  moral  individual  perfection,  we  must  there- 
fore not  merely  introduce  the  idea  of  society,  and  of  the 
fatherland,  but  also,  as  Kant  expressed  it,  we  must 
have  in  view  the  perspective  of  a  future  humanity 
that  will  be  both  better  and  happier.  The  work  of 
reformation  must  be  both  individual  and  social.  It  is 
clear  that  a  rigorous  distinction,  and  especially  a 
formal  opposition  between  individual  and  social 
reform  can  only  be  the  result  of  an  abstraction." 

1  Morale  sociale,  Preface.     Alcan,  1899. 

2  Ib id.,  pp.  279,  291, 


30  INDIVIDUAL  AND   SOCIAL   ETHICS. 

But  must  this  distinction  subsist  under  any  cir- 
cumstances, and  is  not  all  morality  social  morality  ? 
M.  Malapert  thinks  that  the  difference  is  great 
enough  for  one  to  be  definitively  based  on  the 
other,  for  social  duty  to  take  as  its  basis  individual 
duty,  defined  as  "  an  obligation  to  realise  in  one- 
self a  certain  ideal  of  the  human  being  considered 
apart,  a  well-being,  a  personal  best-being.1  "  If  we  do 
not  start  from  the  idea  of  a  duty  towards  oneself,  we 
can  conceive  of  a  social  conduct  but  not  of  a  social 
morality,  but  we  can  never  deduce  from  common 
utility  the  conception  of  a  personal  and  really  ethical 
obligation."  The  principal  reason  M.  Malapert  gives 
for  this  is  that  Plato  and  Aristotle  as  well  as  the 
modern  socialists,  who  closely  subordinate  individual 
conduct  to  sociological  conceptions,  take  as  their 
aim  the  individual,  the  happiness  and  the  perfec- 
tion of  the  individual.  "  All  ethics  which  has  a 
sociological  character  is  essentially  utilitarian  and 
naturalistic." 

The  proof  of  this  does  not  appear  convincing.  As 
Aristotle  claims,  the  perfection  of  the  citizen  may  be 
the  aim  of  the  state,  although  the  perfection  of  the 
state  is  the  aim  of  every  social  organisation,  and 
of  every  moral,  individual,  or  collective  activity; 
this  apparently  vicious  circle  presents  itself  in  every 
organism  in  which  each  element  may  be  taken  both 
as  means  and  end.  The  health  of  the  entire  organism 
is  as  closely  connected  with  the  health  of  the  element 
as  is  the  integrity  of  the  element  with  the  good 
working  of  the  whole  organism. 

Social  morality  has  not  necessarily  as  its  approxi- 
mate aim  the  happiness  of  the  collectivity  or  of  the 

1  Morale  sod  ale  t  p.  287, 


SOCIAL   ETHICS.  31 

individual ;  it  can  only  succeed  in  assuring  this 
happiness  by  prescribing  duties.  No  doubt,  as  M. 
Pillon  remarks,1  it  is  inverting  the  order  of  the  factors 
and  consequences  to  derive  moral  rules  from  laws  in- 
stituted by  wise  legislators  with  a  view  to  general 
utility ;  but  it  is  so  because  "  these  laws  are  imposed 
in  the  name  of  the  just  and  the  good,  because  the 
condition  of  social  institutions  is  a  moral  conception  of 
the  obligation  to  realise  the  good." 

If  we  are  to  believe  M.  Malapert,2  duty  would  first 
of  all  be  an  obligation  towards  oneself.  Guyau3 
denies,  and  M.  Renouvier  is  far  from  affirming,  that 
"  Duty  towards  oneself  appears  in  the  agent,  alone 
and  abstract,  .  .  .  and  is  simply  determined  by  him 
as  a  duty  to  be  himself  with  respect  to  the  different 
possibilities  which  he  imagines,  foresees,  and  by 
which  he  is  attracted." 

This  must  mean  that  the  obligation  wrongly  called 
duty  towards  oneself  is  not,  properly  speaking,  an 
obligation  with  respect  to  any  one,  but  simply  the 
indication  of  a  manner  of  being  imposed  on  a  moral 
agent,  which  is  constrained  to  be  temperate,  wise, 
and  courageous  if  it  desires  to  be  able  to  fulfil  well- 
defined  obligations.  The  latter  are  therefore  logically 
anterior,  although  their  realisation  can  only  be 
chronologically  posterior,  to  the  obligation  of 
being  ready  for  action  as  the  social  ideal  may 
require. 

Besides,  duty  towards  oneself,  or  purely  individual 
duty,  can  only  proceed  from  a  moral  concern  for 
individual  dignity.  Whence  comes  this  "  eminent 
dignity  of  the  human  person,"  of  which  Kant 

1  Annh  philosophique,  1868.  2  Op.  ctf.t  p.  50. 

3  Science  de  la  Morale,  vol.  i.  p.  24. 


32  INDIVIDUAL  AND   SOCIAL   ETHICS. 

speaks  ?  What  has  made  us  conscious  of  it  ?  Our 
"moral"  consciousness?  What,  then,  is  this  con- 
sciousness ? 


17.  The  Moral  Consciousness. 

We  cannot  deny  that  there  is  a  portion  of  our 
psychological  consciousness,  a  part  of  our  representa- 
tions, which,  when  it  is  a  question  of  action,  forms 
a  group  as  distinct  as  possible  from  practical  con- 
ceptions, appetitions,  and  repulsions,  a  group  even 
outside  all  reflection,  and  which  determines  our 
actions,  or  our  judgments  on  the  value  of  actions 
or  of  persons. 

The  Scotch  moralists  and  their  French  disciples 
of  the  beginning  of  the  nineteenth  century,  thought 
that  all  was  explained  when  they  had  affirmed  on  the 
strength  of  certain  phenomena  the  existence  in  us 
of  a  "  moral  sense  "  which  would  enable  us  to  dis- 
tinguish good  from  evil,  the  good  from  the  evil 
and  from  the  less  good,  just  as  another  sense 
enables  us  to  distinguish  red  from  blue  and  one  blue 
from  the  other  shades  of  blue. 

But  just  as  in  our  own  time  the  sensorial  opera- 
tions have  been  analysed,  and  a  multitude  of 
different  psycho-physiological  data  have  been  dis- 
covered which  condition  the  elementary  data  of  our 
senses,  so  psycho-sociology  enables  us  to  perceive 
under  the  different  impressions  of  moral  value  pro- 
duced on  our  minds  by  different  acts  or  different 
persons,  the  very  complex  processes  conditioned  by 
heredity,  temperament,  character,  education,  the 
physical  and  the  social  environment,  and  the  degree 
of  intellectual  and  rational  development. 


THE    MORAL    CONSCIOUSNESS.  33 

The  moral  sense  has  therefore  ceased  to  be  as  it 
were  a  divine  light  placed  within  us  to  guide  and 
enlighten  us  as  to  the  duties  imposed  upon  us  by  our 
noble  origin.  One  would  hardly  dare  in  these  days 
to  say  with  Rousseau1: — "  Conscience,  conscience! 
divine  instinct,  immortal  and  celestial  voice !  certain 
guide  of  beings  who  are  ignorant  and  limited,  but 
free  and  intelligent;  infallible  judge  of  good  and  evil, 
which  makes  man  like  unto  God  I"  We  know  too  wrell 
that  conscience  is  the  resultant,  varying  with  the  age 
and  the  individual,  of  very  different  physical  and 
social  forces,  which  vary  according  to  the  stages 
of  civilisation  through  which  a  tribe  or  a  race  has 
already  passed. 

According  to  Kant,  the  consciousness  does  not 
know  the  good;  it  only  knows  under  what  condition 
the  good  may  exist;  it  is  "  a  law  self-introduced  into 
the  soul,  which  compels  respect  if  not  obedience, 
before  which  all  tendencies  are  dumb,  although 
they  are  working  blindly  against  it;"  it  is  a 
noumenal  liberty,  pure  but  practical  reason;  it  "is 
the  principle  on  which  must  be  based  the  indis- 
pensable condition  of  the  value  that  men  can  attribute 
to  themselves." 

Thus  liberty,  the  ratio  essendi  of  duty,  becomes 
the  foundation  of  human  dignity,  and  therefore 
of  the  so-called  duties  towards  oneself.  But  it 
is  a  fragile  foundation,  for  this  postulated  liberty 
is  not  defined,  nor  is  it  even  conceivable.  Have 
those  who  will  recognise  neither  the  noumenon 
nor  liberty  any  grounds  for  the  recognition  of 
human  dignity  ? 

1  £mile,  Book  IV.         2  Kant,  Critique  of  Pttre  Reason,  p.  269. 


34  INDIVIDUAL    AND    SOCIAL    ETHICS. 

1 8.  The  Data  oj  Reason. 

It  is  correctly  asserted1  that  Kant  endeavoured  to 
obtain  the  formal  conditions  of  morality,  and  that 
after  stripping  the  moral  consciousness  of  every  em- 
pirical datum,  he  found  nothing  remains  but  a  legisla- 
tion which  holds  universally  good  for  every  reasonable 
being.  Let  us  accept  this  positive  datum.  Let  us 
accept,  simply  as  a  fact,  the  reason  within  us.  But 
Kant  attributes  to  all  men,  equally  "  admitting  the 
law  of  duty,"  an  equal  moral  value.  Now;  can  it  be 
denied  that  reason  in  every  individual  is  subject  to  a 
slow  development,  and  that  far  from  being  in  every 
man  at  every  age  the  same,  it  has  a  practical  value 
which  is  quite  different  according  to  the  degree 
attained  by  the  power  of  reflection  ? 

No  doubt  the  conceptions  and  the  principles  of 
which  reason  is  essentially  constituted  in  our  minds 
are  approximately  common  to  all  adult  consciences; 
but  the  use  that  men  make  of  them  and  the  import- 
ance that  they  attach  to  them  are  very  different. 
We  may  admit  the  existence  of  a  rational  tendency 
which  impels  all  humanity,  but  in  different  degrees 
according  to  individuals,  to  seek  the  universality  of 
observed  relations  and  practical  maxims;  this  tend- 
ency causes  all  men,  with  the  minimum  of  reflec- 
tion, to  grasp  the  idea  of  duty,  of  moral  obligation 
in  general.  But  an  idea  as  vague  as  this  is  not 
enough  to  give  to  a  reasonable  being  the  "eminent 
dignity  "  which  makes  him  a  respectable  being  in  his 
own  eyes.  But  does  not  reason  always  furnish  some- 
thing else  besides  the  idea  of  abstract  duty?  The 

1  Delbos,  "  Le  Kantisme  et  la  Science  dela  Morale,"  JRev,  Met.  el 
de  la  Morale,  March  1900. 


RATIONAL   CONDUCT.  35 

voice  of  conscience  is  not  in  fact  as  instructive  as 
is  reflection  on  rational  activity  itself.  The  psycho- 
logical analysis  of  the  concept  of  rational  conduct 
tells  us  much  more  about  duty  and  human  dignity 
than  about  the  a  priori  ideas  of  obligation  or  respect. 

19.  Rational  Conduct. 

For  conduct  to  be  rational,  it  must  not,  as  we 
have  already  seen,  be  inspired  by  ideas,  tendencies, 
or  contradictory  motives.  The  first  principle  of 
reasonable  thought  is  in  fact  that  of  non-contradic- 
tion; hence,  the  voluntary  maintenance  of  the  same 
principles  and  constancy  in  feeling  are  already  a 
guarantee  of  morality.  But  that  is  not  enough  to 
make  us  reasonable,  that  is  to  say  to  enable  us  to 
furnish  a  complete  explanation  of  all  our  acts. 

What  gives  the  reason  of  a  fact,  is  the  law  which 
unites  it  to  others  in  a  constant  manner,  which  brings 
it  into  a  causal  series ;  and  what  gives  the  reason  of 
that  causal  series  is  the  part  that  it  plays  in  a  sum- 
total  of  series  of  the  same  kind — in  a  system.  Is  not 
rational  thought  that  which  links  together  facts  and 
arranges  them  in  an  order  which  gives  to  them  a 
synthetic  unity  ?  Reasonable  conduct,  therefore,  is 
that  which  is  constituted  by  a  series  of  well-linked 
acts,  capable  of  forming  a  systematic  whole. 

"  This  sense  of  the  exact,  of  the  necessary,  and  of 
the  perfect  in  every  type,"  which  M.  Marion  calls 
reason,1  and  which  presides  both  over  our  moral  and 
our  mathematical  judgment,  enables  us  to  establish 
a  hierarchy  of  different  practical  conceptions,  and  to 
award  the  first  importance  to  those  which  sub- 

1  Solidarite  morale,  p.  22. 


36  -    INDIVIDUAL    AND    SOCIAL    ETHICS. 

ordinate  themselves  to  the  rest,  and  then  the 
preference  to  those  which  are  the  most  systematic 
in  themselves,  and  in  the  closest  conformity  to  the 
system  in  which  they  ought  to  find  a  place. 

By  this  subordination  of  the  causal  series  one  to 
another,  and  by  their  subordination  to  the  concep- 
tion of  totality,  men  come  to  have,  as  John  Stuart 
Mill1  puts  it  (and  he  cannot  be  suspected  of  any  tender- 
ness to  such  a  way  of  thinking),  a  natural  tendency 
"to  give  a  most  marked  preference  to  the  manner 
of  existence  which  employs  their  higher  faculties." 
Hence  arises  "  the  sense  of  dignity  which  all  human 
beings  possess,"  as  the  same  philosopher  says,  "  in 
one  form  or  another,  and  in  some,  though  by 
no  means  in  exact,  proportion  to  their  higher 
faculties." 

In  fact  these  faculties  are  the  most  capable  of 
making  us  adopt  and  determine  in  ourselves  a  sys- 
tematic conduct.  But  nothing  can  compel  them 
to  stay  in  the  system  that  constitutes  an  individual; 
nothing  can  prevent  us  from  proceeding  from  any 
system  to  a  more  complex  system,  from  passing  from 
the  individual  to  a  collectivity  at  first  restricted,  but 
afterwards  wide  enough  to  embrace  humanity. 

20.  Duty  and  Moral  Worth. 

From  this  obviously  flows  the  moral  obligation  of 
adopting  a  line  of  conduct  consistent  in  itself  and  in 
harmony  with  a  wider  system  tending  to  realise  the 
highest  conceivable  degree  of  human  activity.  This  is 
the  duty  laid  down  a  priori,  the  duty  on  which  all 
others  are  based.  How  can  we,  in  the  first  place, 

1   Utilitarianism,  p.  12  (nth  edition,  1891). 


DUTY  AND  MORAL  WORTH.  37 

deduce  from  it  a  duty  toward  oneself?  To  the 
moral  consciousness  which,  like  ours,  must  pass,  as 
has  just  been  shown,  from  the  conception  of  the 
widest  system  to  that  of  the  narrowest,  the  individual 
at  first  appears  only  as  a  means  for  the  social  end 
imposed ;  individual  perfection  is  only  a  means 
whereby  the  perfection  of  the  whole  may  be 
realised.  Life  in  society  is,  in  fact,  a  constant 
experience,  if  not  indeed  a  universal  and  necessary 
conception,  which  reason  can  reach  a  priori. 
The  idea  of  the  social  system  is  imposed  on  every 
moral  conscience  that  has  reached  the  stage  in 
which  reflection  points  out  systematic  conduct  as 
universally  obligatory.  The  duty  which  then  appears 
is  the  obligation  to  act  in  view  of  the  realisation  of 
the  best  possible  social  system.  The  individual  who 
fulfils  this  obligation  the  best  is  morally  the  best 
and  the  worthiest.  Thus  we  have  reached  a  general 
explanation  of  the  idea  of  moral  dignity,  which 
serves  as  a  foundation  for  self-respect  and  for  the  so- 
called  duties  towards  oneself.  Our  dignity  is  not 
derived  from  that  "  intrinsic  excellence "  of  persons 
and  things  of  which  M.  Paul  Janet  speaks;  it  seems 
to  us  that  the  "  relations  of  excellence  and  perfec- 
tion "  mentioned  by  Malebranche  as  having  to 
determine  our  esteem  "  and  therefore  the  kind  of 
love  \vhich  esteem  determines,"  can  only  be  based 
on  an  ethico-sociological  foundation.  If  with  Kant 
we  admit  an  absolute  value  which  we  cannot  under- 
stand, we  must  recognise  in  the  individual  a  relative 
moral  value  corresponding  to  his  aptitude  to  fulfil 
a  social  function. 

And   besides,  duties   towards   oneself   are   obliga- 
tions   which    tend    to    the    acquisition    of  "  private 


38  INDIVIDUAL   AND    SOCIAL   ETHICS. 

virtues,"  such  as  wisdom,  courage,  and  tem- 
perance. Now,  have  these  virtues  value  to  any 
other  being  than  a  man  who  lives  in  society  ?  To 
be  wise,  in  the  sense  in  which  we  understand  it  here, 
is  to  possess  knowledge  combined  with  rectitude  of 
judgment.  But  science  is  a  product  of  the  social 
life,  which  is  only  important  from  the  moral  point 
of  view,  because  it  brings  men  into  agreement  on 
objective  notions  and  transforms  certain  private 
beliefs  into  truths  which  are  imposed  on  all.  To 
the  isolated  individual  it  gives  authority,  because 
knowledge  is  foresight  and  power ;  but  this  power 
is  necessary  to  the  individual  whose  civilisation  and 
whose  social  evolution  have  multiplied  his  needs: 
primitive  man  attached  to  it  but  little  value. 
Rectitude  of  judgment  is  of  especial  importance  to 
the  life  of  a  community;  the  unsound  mind,  if  it 
lives  in  isolation,  has  not  less  enjoyment  than 
one  that  is  reasonable.  And  even  if  science  and 
knowledge  were  the  possession  of  a  hermit,  could 
the  great  joy  due  to  the  sentiment  of  intellectual 
perfection,  the  Amor  Dei  Intellectualis  of  a  Spinoza, 
be  considered  as  really  moral  ?  Who  does  not  see 
how  odious  would  be  to  our  modern  conscience  the 
conduct  of  a  man  who  is  prudent  for  himself  alone, 
learned  for  himself  alone,  and  for  his  own  personal 
satisfaction  ?  A  fortiori,  temperance  and  courage  only 
acquire  their  full  value  for  life  in  society.  A  wise, 
courageous,  and  temperate  man  is  of  great  social 
value.  That  is  why  the  virtues  we  called  private 
are  so  important  in  ethics.  They  are  the  very 
condition  of  the  other  civic  virtues.  The  obliga- 
tions which  correspond  to  them  are  therefore  the 
"  requisites  "  of  higher  obligations. 


INDIVIDUAL   DIGNITY.  39 

21.  Individual  Dignity. 

We  are  not. now  raising  the  question  of  depriving 
the  duties  of  the  individual  of  all  value  in  so  far  as  he 
is  an  individual,  or  of  depriving  the  moral  personality 
of  all  dignity.  The  personality  of  the  moral  agent  is 
none  the  less  worthy  of  respect,  even  though  it  may 
not  have  an  absolute  value.  Society  is  not  a  being  in 
itself;  it  is  an  aggregate  of  individuals,  a  system 
of  systems.  The  whole  is  only  of  value  from 
its  elements.  In  the  social  system,  each  of  the 
elements  is  a  will,  a  reason,  a  conscience;  and  it 
must  not  be  forgotten  that  the  "  social  conscience  " 
is  either  a  metaphor,  or  a  totality  of  ideas  and 
sentiments  which  are  found  in  most  individual 
consciences  and  exist  nowhere  else.  The  part 
played  by  invention  in  ethics  has  moreover  been 
already  determined  with  sufficient  precision  to 
clearly  enable  us  to  appreciate  the  whole  value 
which  is  to  be  attached  to  those  individuals,  each 
of  whom  conceives  his  own  ideal,  works  for  the 
progress  of  the  whole,  and  does  his  share  in  the 
realisation  of  an  ideal. 

"The  conspicuous  dignity  of  the  human  person," 
instead  of  being  laid  down  a  priori,  or  deduced  from 
some  metaphysical  postulate,  gains  by  being  based 
on  something  more  solid,  on  considerations  of  a 
sociological  and  psychological  order.  It  appears 
perhaps  less  conspicuous  from  the  moment  that  it 
has  a  less  'mysterious  foundation ;  but  the  respect 
due  to  the  individual  must  have  been  practically 
derived  from  it  alone.  We  must  not  let  ourselves 
be  hypnotised  by  the  ego.  The  doctrine  of  Kant  is 
historically  in  close  connection  with  romanticism, 


40      DIFFERENT   MODES   OF   ETHICAL   RESEARCH. 

which,  as  has  been  justly  observed,  is  based  on  the 
"  hypertrophy  of  the  ego,"  and  also  with  the  French 
Revolution,  which  was  profoundly  saturated,  and  even 
corrupted,  by  a  rampant,  an  outrageous  individual- 
ism. The  moral  activity  is  not  an  art  of  individual 
piety;  it  cannot  subsist  in  the  disregard  of  those 
laws  of  solidarity  which  bring  into  intimate  relation 
the  moral  safety  of  men  of  the  same  generation  and 
that  of  men  of  previous  generations;  and  cannot 
realise  itself  completely  for  one  if,  in  some  measure, 
it  does  not  do  so  for  all.  Individual  morality  must 
therefore  enter  into  social  morality,  and  there  can  be 
in  it  but  one  morality ;  and  that  is  the  theory  which 
dominates  what  is  the  human  art  par  excellence,  the 
art  of  living  in  society,  while  fulfilling  all  the  duties 
which  are  incumbent  on  the  citizens  of  a  given  age 
and  of  a  given  place. 

IV. 

THE  DIFFERENT  MODES  OF  ETHICAL  RESEARCH. 

22.  The  Kantian  Method. 

To  a  new  conception  of  ethics  corresponds  a  new 
method  of  research.  Kant  introduced  an  important 
modification  into  the  method  of  his  predecessors — 
the  rationalistic  philosophers — by  making  the  study 
of  duty  precede  that  of  the  good.  He  rightly  investi- 
gated the  primary  conceptions  on  which  every  moral 
theory  is  necessarily  based ;  but  no  sooner  has  he 
analysed  the  idea  of  good  will  than  he  deduces  from 
it  that  of  spontaneous  and  disinterested  obedience  to 
the  law  of  duty,  and  loses  his  way  in  his  exposition 
of  so-called  postulates,  over  which  mathematical 


THE    KANTIAN    METHOD.  4! 

postulates  have  the  incontestable  advantage  of  being 
infinitely  more  sound.1  The  position  and  the  solu- 
tion of  the  antinomy  of  practical  reason  are,  to  say 
the  least  of  it,  arbitrary,  as  we  shall  see  farther  on. 
And  when  Kant  had  to  enter  into  detail,  by  very 
often  propounding  views  which,  as  we  must  admit, 
were  broad  and  just,  he  made  the  mistake  of  sepa- 
rating "  applied  morality "  so  completely  from 
"  sociological  morality,"  that  the  different  duties  and 
the  different  lawrs  no  longer  seem  more  than  unsound 
adaptations  to  empirical  conditions  of  the  general 
theory  of  duty  and  of  law.  M.  Renouvier  has  also 
admitted  the  separation  of  pure  from  applied  ethics — 
viz.,  the  "  theory  of  life."  However,  duty  in  general 
and  undetermined  moral  obligation  can  only  be  con- 
ceived as  an  abstraction — a  simple  form,  application 
of  which  to  empirical  data  is  immediately  necessary. 
None  of  Kant's  predecessors  made  this  distinction ; 
all  no  doubt  took  count  of  psychological  and  socio- 
logical reality ;  but  they  seem  to  have  been  unwilling 
to  recognise  it,  except  through  the  medium  of  their 
metaphysical  conceptions.  Leibnitz,2  for  instance, 
interpreted  the  facts  of  pleasure  and  happiness  as  the 
marks  of  an  enlargement  of  existence,  and  of  a  dis- 
position towards  moral  perfection,  and  that,  too, 
according  to  a  quite  subjective  opinion  of  the 
theological  value  of  joy  from  the  point  of  view  of 
the  divine  happiness.  Spinoza  drew  a  picture  more 
gcometrico3  of  the  principal  human  passions;  he,  too, 
supposed  that  joy  corresponds  to  a  greater  quan- 

1  Mackenzie,  A  Afanual  of  Ethics,  pp.  56-70  ;    Sidgwick,  History 
of  Ethics,  pp.  271  et  seq. — TR. 

2  Encycl.  Brit.,  Leibnitz,  vol.  xiv.  p.  422. — TR. 

3  Encycl.  Brit.,  Cartesianism,  vol.  v.  p.  152. — TR. 


42      DIFFERENT    MODES    OF    ETHICAL    RESEARCH. 

tity  and  grief  to  a  less  quantity  of  being,  and  that 
we  cannot  have  really  moral  joy  if  the  cause  is  not  in 
ourselves  or  in  God. 

23.  Plato  and  Aristotle. 

Plato  had  apparently  only  one  method.  From  the 
exact  correspondence  laid  down  by  him  between  the 
classes  of  the  State  and  the  parts  of  the  soul,  one 
would  think  that  from  a  kind  of  psychology  he  had 
reached  a  kind  of  social  morality.  The  artisan  class 
has  in  its  collectivity  appetites  and  functions  ana- 
logous to  those  of  the  lower  part  of  the  soul — 
temperance  ought  to  be  recommended  to  them ;  the 
fighting  class  has,  as  the  mean  part  of  the  soul,  that 
force  which  may  be  placed  at  the  service  of  evil 
proclivities  as  well  as  at  the  service  of  wisdom ;  true 
courage  to  them  will  consist  in  moderation,  and  in 
obedience  to  the  counsels  of  the  higher  class,  a  class 
essentially  wise.  Justice  will  thus  be  established  in 
the  State  as  in  the  individual  by  the  subordination 
of  him  who  is  morally  inferior  to  him  who  is  morally 
superior.1  But  we  very  clearly  see  that  in  Plato 
there  are  preconceived  ideas  which  determine  the 
moral  value  a  priori,  apart  from  any  consideration 
of  order,  however  rudimentary  the  scientific  char- 
acter of  that  order  may  be.  The  soul  is  of  divine 
origin,  at  least  as  far  as  its  higher  parts  are  concerned ; 2 
and  it  is  a  stain  on  its  immortal  essence  to  be  united 
to  a  body.  In  the  same  way  the  aristocracy,  the 
class  of  the  wise,  is  of  infinitely  higher  origin  than 
the  class  of  artisans  or  of  labourers.  In  Plato, 

1  Cf.  Republic,  ii.— TR. 

-  Cf.    Timceus,  sect.  91  :  "  The  soul  is  in  the  very  likeness  of  the 
divine;"  Phaedo^  sect.  79. — TR. 


PLATO   AND   ARISTOTLE.  43 

theological    and    aristocratical    prejudices    took    the 
place  of  method.1 

Aristotle  has  applied  to  morality  his  usual  process 
of  investigation,  which  he  expounds  in  many  places, 
but  notably  in  the  Introduction  to  his  "Treatise 
on  the  Soul."  First  he  collects  and  criticises  the 
opinions  of  his  predecessors ;  secondly,  he  seeks  what 
is  necessary  and  essential,  and  endeavours  to  establish 
the  consequences  that  flow  from  the  first  principles 
which  he,  as  a  preliminary,  discovered.  In  ethics, 
after  having  shown  the  characteristics  of  man,  and 
that  his  essence  is  to  think,  and  that  therefore  his 
highest  virtue,  his  characteristic  virtue,  is  the  con- 
templation of  eternal  truths  (theoretical  virtue), 
Aristotle  does  not  forget  that  man  is  necessarily  a 
social  being,  and  that  he  must  carry  into  social 
contingencies  virtues  which  would  fiot  be  becoming 
to  God  or  to  a  divine  being  living  in  isolation. 
Hence  his  theory2  of  the  golden  mean  between  all 
extremes,  a  theory  in  which  one  may  see  the  doc- 
trine of  the  adaptation  of  the  psychological  being  to 
natural  and,  in  particular,  to  social  necessities. 
Thus  morality  becomes  for  Aristotle  a  part  of 
politics;  this  he  states  explicitly  and  rightly.3  He 
cannot  conceive  of  the  wise  man  without  friends, 
and  the  theory  of  friendship  occupies  a  large  place 
in  his  theory  of  ethics.4  A  great  number  of  private 
and  public  virtues  are  carefully  analysed  in  politics 
and  in  ethics  alike.  It  is,  therefore,  to  be  regretted 

1  Cf.  Repiiblic,  viii. ;  The  Statesman,  passim. — TR. 

2  Ethics,  ii.  6.— TR. 

8  Politics,  Book  IV.,  chap.  i.  ;  J.  S.  Mackenzie,  A  Manual  of  Ethics, 
sect.  6,  p.  27.— TR. 

4  Ethics,  Book  VITT.— TR. 


44      DIFFERENT    MODES    OF    ETHICAL    RESEARCH. 

that  the  psychology  and  the  sociology  of  this  great 
thinker -were  not  more  advanced.1 


24.  Adam  Smith. 

The  English  philosophers  in  general,  and  those  of 
the  eighteenth  and  nineteenth  centuries  in  particular, 
thanks  to  their  taste  for  observation  of  detail  and  for 
psychological  research,  have  been  able  to  make  some 
progress  in  the  ethical  method.  "  Doubtless,"  says 
M.  Dugas,2  speaking  of  Adam  Smith,  "  the  choice  of 
sympathy  as  the  sole  basis  for  morals3  may  be  called 
in  question ;  but  not,  in  my  opinion,  the  method  by 
which,  when  once  the  basis  was  chosen,  Adam  Smith 
constructed  on  it  his  ethics."  In  fact,  "  the  theory  of 
the  moral  sentiments  is  primarily  psychological ; " 
and  Adam  Smith  holds  that  morality  springs  from 
the  spontaneous  development  of  tendencies ;  moral 
rules  are  for  him  but  the  summary  of  our  senti- 
mental experience.  He  distinguishes  between 
amiable  virtues  and  those  which  inspire  respect ; 
but  the  former  spring  from  the  effort  of  the  spectator 
to  enter  into  the  sentiments  of  the  person  interested ; 
the  latter,  such  as,  for  instance,  self-control,  spring 
from  the  effort  of  the  person  interested  to  control 
or  influence  the  nerves  or  the  sensibilities  of  others. 
In  this  way  virtue  is  always  referred  to  sentiment. 
Duty  itself  is  always  closely  connected  with  sym- 
pathy, for  the  sentiment  of  moral  obligation  is,  so 

1  Vide   Revue   Philosophiqiie,   January    1901,    an  article    on   "The 
Ethics  of  Antiquity,"  in  which  M.   Brochard  renders  full  justice  to  the 
genius  of  Aristotle,  merely  from  the  point  of  view  of  his  system  of 
morality. 

2  Revue  Philosophique,  t.  xliv.  p.  402,  loc.  cit. 

3  Cf.  Haldane,  Life  of  Adam  Smith,  pp.  61  et  seq.  (Walter  Scott).— 
TR. 


ADAM    SMITH.  45 

to  speak,  a  substitute  for  the  outburst  of  sympathy : 
"  the  moral  rule  is  nothing  more  than  the  example 
of  the  good  tendencies  of  our  hearts  recalled  to  our 
memory.  It  is  a  fact  that  our  sympathy  is  not 
always  awake;  and  further,  persons  whose  absence 
of  sympathy  is  accidental,  may  oppose  to  the  sym- 
pathy which  they  do  not  experience  under  present 
circumstances  the  sympathy  that  they  have  ex- 
perienced under  similar  circumstances.  .  .  .  Duty 
supplies  the  lack  of  sympathy."  Thus,  in  Adam 
Smith,  it  is  the  absence  of  metaphysical  postulates, 
the  predominance  of  a  sentiment,  which  is  rightly 
or  wrongly  affirmed,  .and  which  allows  of  the  sys- 
tematisation  of  all  conduct,  that  M.  Dugas  considers 
as  the  mark  of  a  sound  method  of  moral  research. 

This  is  clear  if  ethics  entirely  consists  of  a  theory 
which,  "  stating  in  precise  terms  and  expanding  the 
idea  of  duty,  is  reduced  almost  to  making  a  complete 
analysis  of  the  psychological  elements  of  the  will;" 
it  is  clear  if  duty  is  nothing  more  than  "  a  sentiment 
or  a  totality  of  sentiments  conscious  of  their  value, 
of  their  power,  and  of  their  direction,  and  trans- 
formed into  custom  and  rule." x  But  to  take  a 
psychological  view  of  morality  is  not  in  my  opinion 
to  embrace  the  whole  field  of  ethics.  We  can  and 
we  ought  to  investigate  the  mental  physiology  of  the 
moral  being;  but  that  is  not  enough  if  it  is  true, 
as  we  have  shown  above,  that  ethics  is  a  theory  of 
life  in  society. 

When  we  have  realised  in  a  being  the  psycho- 
logical ideal,  we  have  done  no  more  than  to  give  a 
good  preparation  for  social  life;  we  have  not  as  yet 
exhibited  the  end  to  be  realised. 

1  Dugas,  loc.  cit. 


46       DIFFERENT    MODES    OF   ETHICAL    RESEARCH. 

25.  Spencer. 

Spencer,  the  theorist  of  evolutionism,  has  simul- 
taneously taken  into  account  the  data  of  biology  or 
psychology,  and  those  of  sociology.  The  "  gener- 
alisations "  afforded  by  these  sciences  are  in  his 
opinion  the  sole  possible  basis  for  "  a  real  theory 
of  balanced  life."  He  has,  therefore,  rightly 
based  human  conduct  in  nature,  and  has  en- 
deavoured to  draw  from  experience  inductions  which 
may  serve  as  principles  for  a  moral  theory. 

Spencer's  ethics  is,  in  short,  as  the  English 
philosopher  has  himself  pointed  out,  a  rational 
utilitarianism.  "  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer,"  says  John 
Stuart  Mill,  "  objects  to  being  considered  an 
opponent  of  utilitarianism,  and  states  that  he  re- 
gards happiness  as  the  ultimate  end  of  morality; 
but  deems  that  end  only  partially  attainable  by 
empirical  generalisations  from  the  observed  results 
of  conduct,  and  completely  attainable  only  by  de- 
ducing from  the  laws  of  life  and  the  conditions  of 
existence,  what  kinds  of  action  necessarily  tend 
to  produce  happiness  and  what  kinds  to  produce 
unhappiness."  l 

Now  the  law  which  dominates  life  is  the  law  of 
evolution,  or  the  passage  from  the  simple  to  the 
complex,  from  the  homogeneous  to  the  hetero- 
geneous, from  the  indefinite  to  the  definite,  by  way 
of  successive  integrations.  That  is  why,  from  the 
physical  point  of  view,  conduct  must  pass  from 
simplicity  of  movement  to  complexity  of  systematised 
action ;  from  the  biological  point  of  view,  it  must 

1  Utilitarianism  (nth  ed.,  1891),  p.  93,  note  (in  a  private  com- 
munication from  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer). 


r  \ 

V*N*VKRS/TY  J 

SPENCER. 


47 


proceed  from  the  accomplishment  of  a  few  vital 
functions  to  the  equilibrium  of  numerous  actions 
tending  to  the  expansion  of  life;  from  the  psycho- 
logical point  of  view,  the  transition  is  from  primitive 
simplicity  of  mind  to  the  continuous  accumulation 
of  experiences,  transmitted  hereditarily  and  ultim- 
ately constituting  certain  faculties  of  moral  intuition  ; 
and  finally,  from  the  sociological  point  of  view,  it 
must  pass  from  primitive  constraint  to  the  agree- 
ment "  of  the  complete  life  of  each  with  the  complete 
life  of  all." 

So  simple  is  the  deduction  which  serves  as  a 
scientific  basis  for  evolutionary  utilitarianism ;  it 
states  in  exact  terms  the  conception  of  happiness, 
which  Mill's  method  left  far  too  indeterminate,  far 
too  dependent  on  free  will,  or  on  the  experience  of 
men  of  the  highest  repute.  Spencer1  tells  us  the 
object  of  the  different  orders  of  functions  of  which 
man  is  constituted,  basing  his  assertions  on  scientific 
observations;  and  he  finds  that  the  realisation  of 
these  ends  coincides  with  "the  greatest  happiness 
of  the  greatest  number,"2  which  may,  therefore,  be 
laid  down  as  the  final  aim  of  morality. 

But  Mr.  Spencer  has  neglected  to  show  that  to 
obey  the  law  of  evolution  is  a  duty.  Hence  he  has 
failed  in  one  of  the  first  obligations  which  are  im- 
posed on  a  moralist,  that  of  laying  down  the  ob- 
ligation. His  ethics  has  remained  naturalistic;  his 
definition  of  the  "good,"  to  be  "sublime,"  is  none 
the  less  empirical.3  To  take  part  in  a  universal 

1  Cf.  Data  of  Ethics,  chap,  ii.— TR. 

2  Edgeworth,  Mathematical  Psychics,  pp.  117  et  seq. — TR. 

3  Goblot,  Essai  sur  la  Classification  des  Sciences,  p.  265.      Alcan, 
1808. 


48      DIFFERENT    MODES    OF    ETHICAL    RESEARCH. 

evolution,  to  realise  a  life  ever  more  powerful  and 
rich,  remains  a  hypothetical  imperative.  "Why 
should  this  universal  good  be  imposed  on  the  will 
of  the  individual  ? "  It  must  be  shown  that  pro- 
gress is  imposed  on  human  thought,  as  soon  as  this 
thought  applies  to  practices  and  to  conduct  the  idea  of 
law,  and  seeks,  in  consequence,  what  is  the  supreme 
law,  not  so  much  of  nature  as  of  the  human  mind. 

26.  Conclusion  on  Method. 

As  long  as  we  confine  ourselves  to  representing 
nature  as  inevitably  obeying  certain  laws,  \ve  are 
free  to  consider  ourselves  as  outside  that  blind 
nature  which  is  the  sport  of  fatality ;  no  obligation 
is  imposed  on  us.  But  as  soon  as  human  thought  is 
exhibited  to  us  as  obeying  in  its  turn  certain  laws, 
conceiving  a  principle  as  necessary  and  therefore 
obligatory — that  of  seeking  everywhere  for  causes,  or 
that  of  establishing  out  of  every  diversity  a  system 
— from  that  moment  duty  is  laid  down. 

The  preliminary  step  in  ethical  research  is  there- 
fore the  establishment  of  moral  obligation,  and  the 
enunciation  of  its  general  form.  We  have  seen 
above  *  that  the  idea  of  rational  activity  is  imposed 
on  us  because,  owing  to  our  mental  constitution,  we 
cannot  form  any  other  conception ;  that  the  idea  of 
that  rational  activity  embraces  the  idea  of  system, 
and  involves  as  duty  in  general  the  obligation  of 
realising  in  the  whole  domain  of  human  life  a 
system  of  systems,  a  perfect  co-ordination  of  all  the 
individual  and  social  functions. 

Such    being    the    outcome    of    our    preliminary 

1   Vide  Section  19. 


CONCLUSION    ON    METHOD.  49 

investigations,  our  researches  ought  to  be  pursued 
independently  of  any  hypothesis,  and  therefore  in- 
dependently even  of  the  Spencerian  conception  of 
universal  evolution,  at  first  in  the  order  of  psycho- 
physiological  facts,  and  then  in  the  order  of  psycho- 
sociological  facts.  Thus  the  second  step  will  be 
constituted  by  a  study  of  the  psychological  and 
social  conditions  of  moral  action. 

But  we  might  be  reproached  with  falling  into  too 
exclusive  a  naturalism  if  we  content  ourselves  with 
establishing  the  actual  nature  of  the  moral  being  and 
the  direction  of  evolution.  We  have  seen  above  that 
morality  is  not  a  science  or  a  part  of  science,  but 
rather  a  technology,  and  that  the  most  general  of  all ; 
and  that  if  based  on  a  science  it  must  be  distinguished 
from  it  by  a  construction  of  the  ideal.  This  is  the 
third  step  in  our  investigations. 

Now,  to  avoid  the  a  priori  constructions  which  up 
to  now  have  been  the  basis  of  the  greater  part  of 
morality,  utilitarian  ethics  included,  we  must  rely  as 
little  as  possible  on  imagination,  and  must  keep  as 
close  as  possible  to  scientific  data.  If  we  admit  that 
the  social  evolution  and  the  mental  constitution  of 
the  individual  are  perfectly  systematic  and  coherent, 
we  will,  not  have  to  seek  a  higher  ideal.  If  we  admit 
incompatible  tendencies,  vices,  faults,  and  excesses 
which  are  injurious  to  the  harmony  of  the  whole 
and  to  the  co-ordination  of  the  functions,  whether 
individual  or  collective,  our  duty  is  to  indicate  what 
ought  to  be  suppressed,  developed,  or  created,  in 
order  that  the  system  may  be  at  the  same  time  as 
rich  and  as  harmonious  as  possible.  It  is  on  this 
point  that  the  opinions  of  moralists  may  differ,  but 
we  shall  see  that  the  divergence  may  be  of  slight 

4 


5O    .  DIFFERENT    MODES    OF    ETHICAL    RESEARCH. 

importance  if  the  different  writers  keep  equally  close 
to  the  facts  and  to  legitimate  inductions. 

Finally,  there  comes  a  fourth  step.  When  the 
causes  of  vice  and  moral  error,  of  social  and  in- 
dividual disorder  have  been  determined,  they  must 
next  be  eliminated  from  real  life.  The  moralist 
must  therefore  indicate  the  means  most  suitable  for 
the  struggle  against  immorality  and  for  the  realisa- 
tion of  the  ideal.  The  knowledge  of  these  means 
flows  from  that  of  the  causes  of  disorder ;  when  wre 
know  the  nature  of  the  evil  and  its  source,  we  can 
point  out  the  remedies. 

What  is  a  moral  theory  thus  established  ?  Ac- 
cording to  M.  Pillon,  a  morality  which  recognises 
no  relation  or  link  with  metaphysics  can  only  be  a 
morality  of  sentiment.  No  doubt  it  would  be  so  if 
our  method  implied  renunciation  of  the  indisputable 
right  of  human  reason  to  co-ordinate  sentiments 
whether  individual  or  collective,  and  to  judge  them 
by  a  general  criterion,  that  of  their  aptitude  to  form 
part  of  a  rational  system.  But  our  method,  on  the 
contrary,  makes  of  its  resultant  theory  a  real  morality 
of  duty,  both  individual  and  social,  of  human  duty, 
in  every  meaning  of  the  phrase. 


PART  II. 

THE    PSYCHOLOGICAL    IDEAL. 

I.  THE  MORAL  WILL. 

27.  Pure  Practical  Reason — 28.  Moral  Action,  Voluntary 
Action — 29.  Perceptio?i,  Conception,  and  Imagination — 
30.  Attention  and  Association — 31.  Perception  and  the 
Scnsorial  Type — 32.  Self-perception — 33.  Instability  and 
Aboulia — 34.  Deliberation — 35.  The  Conscious  Processes 
— 36.  Irreflection  and  Good  Manners — 37.  The  Choice  of 
the  Best — 38.  Priority  of  the  Tendency  over  the  Idea 
of  the  Good — 39.  Moral  Subjectivism — 40.  Unification  of 
Tendencies  a?id  Heredity  —  41.  The  Reason  —  42.  The 
Union  of  Different  Tendencies  and  of  Reason. 

II.  LIBERTY  AND  MORALITY. 

43.  Kant  and  Free-will — 44.  The  Origin  of  Character — 
45.  Science,  Conscience,  and  Liberty — 46.  Belief  and 
Liberty — 47.  The  Person  the  Real  Agent — 48.  Conclusion. 

III.  MORAL  TENDENCIES. 

49.  Different  Tendencies,  Different  Doctrines — 50.  Natural- 
ism— 51.  Hedonism — 52.  Epicureanism — 53.  Utilitarian- 
ism —  54.  Interest  and  Desire  —  55.  Egoism  —  56.  The 
Collective  Interest  —  57.  Intellectual  Happiness  —  58. 
Mysticism — 59.  The  Ethics  of  Spinoza — 60.  The  Stoic 
Morality  —  61.  The  ^Esthetic  Sentiment  —  62.  The 
Altruistic  Tendencies — 63.  Generosity  —  64.  Sociability 
— 65.  Tendency  to  Social  Organisation. 

IV.  THE  MORAL  INDIVIDUAL. 

66.  The  Psychological  Ideal  and  Moral  Firmness — 67. 
Moderation — 68.  Virtue  and  Truth — 69.  The  Cult  of 
the  Beautiful — 70.  Joy — 71.  Risk  and  Exercise. 

51 


52  THE    MORAL   WILL. 

V.  THE  DETERMINISM  OF  IMMORAL  ACTIONS. 

72.  Crime — 73.  Crime  and  the  Criminal — 74.  Classifica- 
tion and  Descriptive  Summary — 75.  The  Criminal  by 
Accident — 76.  Insane  Criminals — 77.  Immorality  of  the 
Imbecile  —  78.  Intelligent  Degenerates  —  79.  The  Un- 
balanced—  80.  The  Criminal  by  Passion  —  81.  The 
Obsessed —  82.  Exaggeration  of  Good  Sentiments  —  83. 
Moral  Vertigo — 84.  The  Criminal  Type — 85.  Immoral 
Effects  of  Solidarity — 86.  Effects  of  Heredity,  Alcoholism, 
and  Social  Disturbajices  in  General. 


I. 

THE  MORAL  WILL. 

27.  Pure  Practical  Reason. 

WHAT  Kant  has  considered  in  man  is  reason 
become  practical,  but  remaining  pure,  and  remote 
from  any  alliance  with  experience.  That  is  why 
his  ethics  is  not  a  theory  of  human  conduct.  If 
he  had  been  more  of  a  psychologist  and  less  of  a 
metaphysician,  Kant  would  have  seen  the  necessity 
of  taking  into  account  sensibility,  tendencies,  inclina- 
tions, and  desires,  in  some  other  way  than  to  declare 
them  hostile  to  practical  reason.  Aristotle,  more  in 
the  habit  of  noting  the  complexity  of  psychological 
and  biological  phenomena,  had  taken  pains  on  the 
contrary  to  show  that  pure  intellect  cannot  of  itself 
determine  action ;  that  its  role  in  the  control  of 
appetite  and  of  tendencies  corresponding  to  sensible 
knowledge  is  limited.1  Spinoza  was  no  doubt  in- 
spired by  Aristotle  when  he  asserted  that,  in  order 
to  combat  the  passions,  reason  must  determine  an 

1  Cf.  De  Anima,  Book  III.,  and  the  Nicomachean  Ethics. 


MORAL    ACTION,    VOLUNTARY   ACTION.  53 

affection,  the  "  amor  Dei  intellectuals " ; l  but 
Spinoza  was  too  deeply  penetrated  with  intellectuality 
to  appreciate  the  importance  of  empirical  know- 
ledge, and  of  the  affections  which  flow  therefrom ; 
the  wise  man  he  describes  seems  to  have  to  forget 
that  he  is  a  man,  and  only  conceives  himself  as  part 
of  God. 


28.  Moral  Action,  Voluntary  Action. 

Psychology  has  taught  contemporary  moralists  a 
wider  appreciation  of  the  nature  and  conditions  of 
moral  activity,  which  is  essentially  a  voluntary 
activity.  Although  Spencer  dimly  sees  as  realisable 
in  a  distant  future  an  ideal  of  quite  instinctive 
morality,  we  need  not  to  hesitate  to  affirm  that 
voluntary  decision,  choice  after  deliberation,  will 
remain  the  characteristic  of  the  moral  act  from  the 
psychological  point  of  view,  as  long  as  there  is  any 
theoretical  controversy  and  hesitation  in  practice, 
that  is  to  say,  as  long  as  human  nature  is  what  we 
know  it  to  be.  Why,  in  fact,  do  we  generally  refuse 
to  recognise  morality  in  animals,  at  least  in  the 
sense  in  which  we  use  the  word  in  speaking 
of  man  ?  It  is  not  so  much  from  theological  prejudice 
or  from  metaphysical  belief  in  the  absence  on  the  one 
side,  or  in  the  presence  on  the  other,  of  a  liberty 
assumed  to  be  indispensable  to  the  formation  of  a 
moral  conscience,  as  from  the  lack  of  reflection, 
deliberation,  and  rational  choice  in  the  animal. 
Beings  inferior  to  man  give  way  in  almost  all  their 
actions  to  instinctive  tendencies,  in  perfect  harmony 

1  Cf.  Ethics,  Books  IV.  and  V. 


54  THE    MORAL   WILL. 

with  the  exigencies  of  their  situation  and  their  en- 
vironment and  their  nature;  so  that  all  their  actions 
are,  so  to  speak,  automatic,  although  they  may 
bear  the  mark  of  sympathy,  of  altruism,  and  even  of 
disinterestedness. 

Moral  theory  and  scientific  thought  could  not 
exercise  their  influence  on  instinctive  conduct, 
whether  entirely  imitative  or  springing  from  the 
reproduction,  spontaneous  or  habitual,  of  anterior 
modes  of  action.  They  can  only  influence  the  con- 
duct of  a  being  capable  of  modifying  his  manner 
of  action  according  to  circumstances,  accord- 
ing to  the  thoughts  which  become  preponderant 
in  the  mind  after  deliberation  and  reflection. 
We  must  therefore  consider  in  the  moral 
being  the  being  which  is  capable  of  voluntary 
decision. 

As  a  rule,  we  consider  three  stages  in  the  fact  of 
will:  first  the  conception,  either  of  several  \ pos- 
sible courses,  or  simply  of  an  action  that  it  is 
still  possible  to  accomplish  or  not  to  accomplish, 
of  a  fact  that  it  is  possible  to  realise  or  not  to 
realise;  secondly,  deliberation,  or  the  evocation  of 
different  motives  and  the  ensuing  struggle  between 
the  motives;  thirdly,  the  choice,  which  constitutes 
the  end  of  the  deliberation  and  the  commencement 
of  the  transition  to  the  phase  of  movement  and  in- 
hibition. 

This  distinction  is  not  based,  as  we  shall  see,  on 
the  different  nature  of  the  three  operations,  which, 
on  the  contrary,  overlap  and  form  but  one  and  the 
same  act;  but  we  may  take  it  into  account  in  the 
analysis  of  so  complex  a  fact  as  the  voluntary 
phenomenon. 


PERCEPTION,    CONCEPTION,    AND    IMAGINATION.      55 

29.  Perception,  Conception,  and  Imagination. 

In  moral  action  it  is  a  question  of  knowing  which 
of  several  possible  acts  or  of  the  two  terms  of  an  al- 
ternative respond  best  to  the  general  idea  that  one  has 
of  the  good  or  of  duty.  Now,  to  conceive  unusual 
modes  of  action,  generous  or  dangerous,  noble  and  dis- 
interested, is  not  the  act  of  a  common  intelligence, 
at  any  rate  under  trivial  circumstances.  Hence  the 
imagination  plays  an  important  part  in  the  initial 
phase  of  moral  action. 

The  physiology  of  the  mind,  as  far  as  the  imagination 
is  concerned,  is  familiar  enough.1  We  know  that  the 
imagination  is  dependent  far  more  than  is  apparent 
on  anterior  experience.  The  artist  does  not  conceive 
the  beautiful  without  having,  first  of  all,  collected 
from  one  side  or  another  the  different  materials  of  its 
construction;  in  the  same  way  the  most  beneficent 
being  does  not  at  once,  and  without  preparation,  or 
education,  or  exercise,  or  preliminary  experience, 
conceive  of  the  most  meritorious  acts.  Certainly 
he  does  not  need  examples  such  as  he  may  merely 
reproduce  with  unimportant  changes;  he  is  not  a 
mere  imitator,  although  more  prone  than  one  would 
suppose  to  slavish  imitation.  Sometimes  lie  changes 
the  nature  of  an  act  previously  accomplished  by  him- 
self or  by  another  before  his  eyes,  either  by  adding 
to  it,  or  taking  from  it,  or  by  combining  it  with 
another  which  furnishes,  as  it  were,  a  complement; 
sometimes  he  takes  from  here  or  there  different 
elements  to  form  a  new  whole.2 

1  This  is  due  in  a  large  measure  to  M.  Ribot's  work  entitled  V Ima- 
gination cicatrice.     Alcan,  1900. 

2  Cf,  G.  F.  Stout,  Manual  of  Psychology i  vol.  ii.  chap.  iv. — TR, 


56  THE    MORAL   WILL. 

The  operation  takes  place  outside  the  sphere  of  the 
clear  consciousness;  it  is  unintentionally,  and  with 
no  clear  conception  of  the  physical  act  which  is 
accomplished,  that  the  mind  dissociates  the  data 
involved  in  different  experiences,  and  then  associates 
them  and  makes  of  them  an  original  synthesis.  The 
laws  of  spontaneous  attention  explain  the  dissocia- 
tion, and  those  of  cerebral  and  mental  association 
explain  the  synthesis. 

30.  Attention  and  Association. 

Attention  is  spontaneously  paid  in  a  present 
totality  to  the  elements  which  present  a  particular 
interest  to  the  satisfaction  of  a  more  Or  less  profound 
tendency.  When  the  tendency  is  profound  it  is 
lasting,  and  its  effects  are  constant;  the  attention 
always  follows  the  same  direction.  In  the  same  way 
a  sporting  dog  which  has  a  hereditary  tendency  to 
seek  after  game  recognises  a  number  of  objects  only 
because  they  are  favourable  to  the  gratification  of 
his  tendency;  just  as  a  Newfoundland  dog  of  which 
Romanes1  speaks  only  observed  in  a  hatchet  and  in 
an  iron  wedge,  which  his  master  regularly  used  to 
split  wood,  this  common  property  of  serving  to  split 
wood — so  much  so  that  when  sent  to  find  the 
hatchet  and  not  finding  it,  he  brought  the  wedge. 
In  the  same  way,  the  moral  being  who  has  a  keen 
desire  to  play  a  beneficent  part  in  society  spon- 
taneously attends  to  all  that  in  the  acts  of  his  fellows 
and  in  his  own  acts  presents  a  character  peculiarly 
favourable  to  the  realisation  of  his  desire.  And  from 
a  large  number  of  experiences  accumulated  under  the 

1  Animal  Intelligence. 


ATTENTION   AND   ASSOCIATION.  57 

same  conditions  is  thus  detached  a  more  and  more 
important  group  of  elements,  more  or  less  suited  for 
combination,  but  all  favourable  to  the  conception  of 
good  actions. 

Their  combination  will  take  place  according  to  the 
laws  of  systematic  association  so  well  exhibited  by 
M.  Paulhan.1  No  doubt  it  is  of  importance  that  the 
different  materials  to  be  associated  have  determined 
in  the  brain  modifications  of  neighbouring  neurons 
ready  to  associate  either  by  pushing  their  protoplasmic 
prolongations  towards  one  another,  or  by  triumphing 
over  the  obstacle  in  the  way  of  their  direct  com- 
munication by  a  variable  quantity  of  neuroglia,2  as 
W.  James3  has  argued,  so  that  the  cerebral  conti- 
guity must  have  rendered  mental  association  possible ; 
but  to  explain  that  this  association  is  this  parti- 
cular synthesis  and  not  another,  formed  of  certain 
elements  to  the  exclusion  of  a  great  number  of  others, 
we  must  have  recourse  to  the  following  -principle: 
anterior  data,  capable  of  forming  a  systematic 
whole  corresponding  to  the  tendency  which  directs 
the  mental  future  of  the  subject  at  the  moment 
under  consideration,  are  the  only  data  which 
associate. 

We  see  how  far  dissociation  as  well  as  associa- 
tion, equally  necessary  to  the  conception  of  acts 
that  are  capable  of  becoming  moral,  are  dependent 
on  individual  inclinations.  The  importance  of  these 
factors  of  the  mental  life,  however,  ought  not  to 
make  us  forget  the  part  that  is  played  by  the  percep- 
tions themselves.  On  the  contrary,  the  preliminary 

1  L! Activite  mentale  et  les  Elements  de  I' Esprit.     Paris,  Alcan. 

2  [Connective  tissues.] 

3  Princ iples  of  Psychology,  vol.  i.  pp.  561  et  seq. 


50  THE    MORAL   WILL. 

examination  of  this  role  will  the  better  bring  to  light 
the  scope  of  the  tendencies,  whether  fundamental  or 
acquired,  of  the  individual,  and  of  the  group  to  which 
he  belongs. 

31.  Perception  and  the  Sensorial  Type. 

The  perception  of  objects  is  not  pure  passivity. 
As  W.  James1  has  shown,  and  as  experiments  which 
may  be  easily  repeated  will  prove,  one  only  perceives 
objects  from  one  point  of  view  by  calling  attention  to 
certain  characters  alone,  while  others  remain  in  the 
background;  and  as  all  perception  consists  in  con- 
struction superadded  to  actual  sensorial  data — and  in 
a  spontaneous  interpretation  of  these  actual  data 
by  means  of  anterior  data,  which,  being  immediately 
evoked,  blend  with  present  sensations — we  must 
recognise  that  objective  perception  is,  like  imagina- 
tion, dependent  on  the  tendencies  which  determine 
the  course  of  thought.  But  further,  certain  sensorial 
data,  both  present  and  recalled,  are  more  favoured 
than  others  according  to  the  sensorial  type  that  a 
given  individual  realises.  This  has  its  importance 
from  the  point  of  view  of  action;  in  fact,  the  ex- 
aggeration of  any  type  whatever,  of  the  auditive  type, 
or  the  visual  type,  is  only  produced  in  general  to  the 
detriment  of  the  qualities  which  pertain  to  another 
type — the  motor  type,  for  example.  Now  the  sen- 
sorial type  determines  the  imaginative  and  associa- 
tive type,  the  type  of  recollections,  of  abstractions,  in 
short,  a  complete  aspect  of  mental  life.  An  "  audi- 
tive "  or  a  "  visual "  person  will  have  a  more  or  less 
marked  tendency  not  to  act  as  an  "  indifferent "  or  as 

1  Of>.  cit.,  chap,  xix.,  vol.  ii.  pp.  76  el  seij. — TR. 


SELF-PERCEPTION.  59 

a  "  motor " ;  he  runs  the  risk  of  quite  a  different 
conception  of  the  modes  of  activity;  the  conduct  of 
an  artist,  a  painter,  a  sculptor,  or  a  musician  who 
"  visualises "  or  "  hears "  with  an  intensity  which 
sometimes  lands  him  on  the  threshold  of  hallucina- 
tion will  not  have  the  same  aspect,  or  perhaps  even 
the  same  principles,  as  the  conduct  of  a  workman 
who  realises  the  motor  type,  or  of  a  tradesman  whose 
type  has  remained  undetermined. 

We  are  constantly  seeing  artists,  musicians 
especially,  make  themselves  remarkable  by  some 
eccentricity  in  their  conduct;  we  find,  on  the  other 
hand,  that  different  subjects,  with  an  average  apti- 
tude to  experience  every  kind  of  sensation,  have  not 
only  plenty  of  good  sense  from  the  purely  intellectual 
point  of  view,  but  also  a  well-marked  taste  for 
moderation  in  conduct  and  for  regularity  in  morals. 

If  we  now  endeavour  to  discover  why  the  sensorial 
diverges  from  the  indifferent  type,  we  must  attribute 
a  very  nearly  equal  share  to  the  influence  of  heredity, 
which  is  manifested  by  the  organic  aptitudes  and  the 
congenital  tendencies  of  the  mind,  and  to  the  influence 
of  education,  habits,  and  acquired  tendencies. 

32.  Self -perception. 

The  nature  of  special  aptitudes  from  the  point 
of  view  of  sensation  and  perception  is  of  great  im- 
portance, particularly  in  relation  to  action,  because  of 
the  quite  peculiar  manner  in  wrhich  the  subject  per- 
ceives itself,  according  to  the  sensorial  type  to  which 
it  belongs.  One  point  that  the  psychologists  have  not, 
as  a  rule,  thrown  into  sufficient  relief,  is  that  of 
personal  perception.  It  has  often  been  said  that  we 


60  THE    MORAL   WILL. 

perceive  ourselves  just  as  we  perceive  objects  external 
to  us;  sufficient  stress  has  not  been  laid  on  the  con- 
sequences of  this  objective  representation,  which  is 
much  more  complex  than  the  idea  of  the  ego  upon 
which,  almost  exclusively,  the  attention  of  philo- 
sophers has  been  fixed.  The  idea  of  the  ego  and  the 
perception  of  self  are  two  physical  facts  as  different 
as  the  conception  of  a  body  in  general  and  the  con- 
crete representation  of  a  determined  body.  If  to 
apprehend  oneself  is  a  mental  operation  analogous  to 
every  other  objective  apprehension,  we  imagine  more 
than  we  find ;  we  reinstate  many  more  elements  than 
are  actually  given;  we  fuse  the  past  and  the  present. 
In  accordance  with  certain  sensations,  for  the  most 
part  organic,  we  conceive  ourselves  as  concrete  beings 
habitually  presenting  definite  characters,  in  which  we 
have  taken  more  note  in  the  past  of  certain  aspects 
than  of  others,  according  to  the  constantly  predomi- 
nant tendency  of  our  mind,  according  to  the  sense  of 
experience  which  is  most  pronounced  in  us.  If  one 
person  perceives  himself  in  particular  qua  an  auditive 
or  more  especially  qua  a  "  speculative  or  an  in- 
tellectual," another  will  perceive  himself  most  often 
as  a  "  motor,"  in  particular,  and  more  especially,  as 
active  and  practical.  No  doubt  we  perceive  our- 
selves in  situations  so  different  that  the  same  in- 
dividual may  be  turning  attention  sometimes  to  his 
speculative  aptitudes,  and  sometimes  to  his  practical 
aptitudes;  but  it  is  none  the  less  true  that  each  of 
us  has  a  usual  way  of  conceiving  himself  dependent 
on  the  habitual  preponderance  in  clear  consciousness 
of  muscular  images  and  sensations  in  preference,  for 
instance,  to  auditory  or  visual  images. 

Can  it  be  denied  that  this  exercises  the  greatest 


INSTABILITY   AND   ABOULIA.  6l 

influence  over  the  nature  of  the  acts  which  we  con- 
ceive ?  An  action  is  always  the  action  of  a  deter- 
mined person,  and  to  conceive  it  is  to  conceive  the 
accomplishment  of  a  movement,  or  a  series  of  move- 
ments, by  a  given  agent.  We  represent,  more  or  less 
vaguely,  and  always  from  some  specific  point  of  view, 
a  concrete  being.  This  being  has  certain  habitual 
characteristics,  and  some  aspects  of  its  nature  have 
caught  our  attention  more  than  others;  and  if  we  are 
ourselves  the  agent,  we  clearly  only  conceive  that 
which  can  have  the  closest  relations  to  our  own 
nature.  In  other  words,  because  we  cannot  separate 
the  act  from  the  agent,  the  conception  of  an  act  that 
we  can  accomplish  cannot  be  separated  from  the 
concrete  representation  that  we  have  of  ourselves. 
And  that  is  why  an  athlete,  whose  mind  is  full  of 
images  of  struggle,  exercises,  and  muscular  con- 
tractions, etc.,  who  perceives  himself  habitually  not 
so  much  an  intelligent  and  reasonable  being,  as  a 
vigorous  organism  and  a  system  of  powerful  muscles, 
will  more  readily  conceive  of  recourse  to  force  and 
violence  than  of  recourse  to  argument,  to  dialectic, 
or  to  persuasion. 


33.  Instability  and  Aboulia. 

Men  having  neither  stable  temperament  nor  firm 
character,  easily  change  their  type,  and  in  certain 
pathological  cases  successively  exhibit  different  as- 
pects (the  alternating  personalities  of  hysterical 
subjects),  and  sometimes  experience  a  great  diffi- 
culty in  conceiving  action ;  it  seems  as  if  the  source 
of  practical  life  is  exhausted  in  them.  We  call  them 
aboulic,  but  they  lack  will  especially  because  of  their 


62  THE    MORAL   WILL. 

mental  instability,  which  prevents  them  from  having 
a  clear  conception  of  themselves.  Defective  personal 
perception  involves  more  or  less  marked  defect  in 
practical  conceptions.  How  could  such  beings  ever 
raise  themselves  very  high  in  the  moral  hierarchy  ? 

No  idea  attains  in  their  mind  sufficient  clearness 
to  determine  voluntary  action,  or  even  to  arouse 
deliberation;  for  clearness  of  representations  in 
general,  and  of  practical  conceptions  in  particular, 
proceeds  from  the  attention  which  is  given  to  them— 
that  is  to  say,  in  short,  from  their  agreement  with 
the  deeply  rooted  and  constant  tendencies  of  a 
subject.  When  the  tendencies  are  only  fugitive, 
there  is  only  weakness  of  attention,  and  therefore 
incapacity  from  the  practical  point  of  view ;  and 
what  better  sign  could  be  found  of  the  instability  of 
tendencies  than  the  absence  of  a  constant  self-con- 
ception, of  a  personal  perception  varying  insensibly 
save  in  details  of  secondary  importance  ? 

To  sum  up:  the  first  stage  of  moral  action,  the 
conception  of  practical  possibilities,  appears  to  us  as 
a  psychological  fact  varying  with  the  individual  but 
closely  connected  with  his  character,  and  of  the 
highest  importance  from  the  point  of  view  of  eleva- 
tion, value,  and  of  decision  itself.  For  if  the  choice 
is  made  among  the  possible  courses  that  are  con- 
ceived, how  can  we  choose  acts  which  are  wide  in 
their  moral  scope  if  we  are  found  incapable  of  con- 
ceiving such  acts  ? 

34.  Deliberation. 

The  conception  of  an  act  as  simply  possible,  and 
not  as  necessary,  involves  the  consideration  of  the 


DELIBERATION.  63 

following  question:  Will  it  be  realised,  will  it  be  in 
the  form  in  which  it  was  conceived,  or  in  a  new  form 
requiring  a  new  conception  (which  this  time  is  made 
in  the  course  of  deliberation,  in  virtue  of  the  incessant 
modification  of  the  content  of  the  consciousness)  ? 

It  may  be  affirmed  that  in  most  voluntary  acts,  if 
not  in  all,  the  primitive  conceptions  are  modified  by 
the  sole  fact  that  one  hesitates  in  their  immediate 
realisation,  and  that  they  are  submitted  to  an  ex- 
amination. In  fact  this  examination  is  always 
arousing  motives  and  sentiments  in  favour  of  or 
opposed  to  the  project  in  question,  which  thus 
appears  in  a  new  form  at  every  step  taken  in  the 
process  of  deliberation.  As  M.  Bergsen  has  clearly 
pointed  out,1  we  too  often  neglect  to  consider  the 
incessant  progress  made  in  the  mind  by  a  practical 
idea  of  which  we  are  examining  the  advantages  and 
the  disadvantages;  instead  of  remaining  fixed  as  a 
thing,  this  idea  participates  in  the  movement  of  the 
thought,  in  the  life  of  the  "soul"  that  totality  of 
images,  of  ideas,  of  emotions,  and  of  actions,  the 
existence  of  wrhich  is  conditioned  by  instability. 
Sometimes,  deliberation  and  conception  have  been 
contrasted,  not  only  as  we  have  just  contrasted  them, 
for  the  purposes  of  analysis,  but  by  distinguishing 
them  carefully  one  from  another,  as  two  successive 
phases  which  cannot  overlap.  To  deliberate,  how- 
ever, is  in  a  sense  to  continue  the  work  of  the  con- 
ception of  an  act  until  the  synthesis  of  the  motor 
images  is  sufficiently  powerful  in  the  consciousness 
to  determine  the  corresponding  muscular  exertions. 

But  at  this  second  stage  it  is  no  longer  imagina- 
tion, mental  association,  and  memory  which  play  the 

1  Les  Donnces  iinnudiates  de  la  Conscience. 


64  THE    MORAL    WILL. 

principal  role;  it  is  the  sentiments,  the  emotions,  and 
the  tendencies,  the  reasonings  and  the  beliefs. 

A  practical  idea  arises  in  the  mind  by  the  partly 
sub-conscious  play  which  we  have  described  above; 
it  immediately  pleases  or  displeases;  it  is  in  conflict 
with  or  is  favoured  by  certain  beliefs;  it  is  in  agree- 
ment or  disagreement  with  certain  principles,  pre- 
judices, scientific  axioms,  or  simple  judgments  of 
the  aesthetic  taste;  and  finally,  with  the  aid  of  certain 
general  propositions,  the  mind  deduces  the  particular 
consequences  of  the  act  proposed;  or  rather,  that  act 
is  brought  into  relation  with  other  particular  analo- 
gous facts,  and  from  them  is  derived  a  particular 
rule,  which  is  or  is  not  in  harmony  with  rules  which 
have  been  previously  admitted.  This  is  a  summary 
description  of  the  processus  of  deliberation ;  the  pro- 
cessus  is  repeated  more  or  less  completely  as  many 
times  as  the  idea  is  even  ever  so  slightly  modified; 
so  that  sometimes  deliberation  is  of  considerable 
duration,  which  may  be  an  index  of  the  always  very 
great  complexity  of  such  a  mental  act. 

It  is  easily  seen  that  when  it  is  a  question  of  a 
moral  act  to  be  deliberately  accomplished,  the  nature 
of  the  psychic  processus  is  very  complex.  Kant,1  in  his 
far  too  summary  psychology,  only  admitted  one  motive 
of  moral  conduct ;  he  held  that  only  the  sentiment  of 
respect  for  the  law  of  duty,  an  a  priori  sentiment,  and 
the  only  one  we  can  conceive  as  necessary,  should  de- 
termine the  choice  of  the  reasonable  being.  Delibera- 
tion could  not  therefore  be  of  long  duration,  hesitation 
was  not  permitted,  all  other  sentiments  but  moral 
respect  being  at  once  avoided  as  "  pathological." 

1  Cf.  Bradley,  Ethical  Studies,  Essay  iv. ;  Mackenzie,  op.  cit.,  chap. 
v.  ;  Sidj  wick,  Outlines  of  the  History  of  Ethics t  p.  272.  — TR. 


DELIBERATION.  65 

It  is  true,  no  doubt,  that  Kant  recognised  that 
whatever  be  a  man's  morality  he  has  never  yet  acted 
out  of  pure  respect  for  the  moral  law.  His  theory, 
ipso  facto,  applies  to  superhuman  beings.  An  ethical 
doctrine  which  professes  to  direct  the  conduct  of 
men  ought  to  take  into  account  the  psychological 
complexity  of  our  nature.  "  Nothing,"  says  M. 
Renouvier,1  "  could  do  more  to  prevent  the  diffusion 
of  the  principles  of  Kant  in  the  world  than  to 
require — so  uselessly  for  the  foundations  of  this 
theory,  so  vainly  \vhen  wre  consider  man  as  he  is 
constituted,  and  even  human  nature  as  w-e  can 
understand  it — that  action,  to  be  morally  good, 
must  be  exempt  from  passion.  He  himself  con- 
fessed that  he  did  not  know  if  any  action  of  the 
kind  had  ever  taken  place;  and  I  may  add,  that 
I  do  not  know  if  the  purely  rational  agent,  sup- 
posing such  an  agent  were  possible,  would  be 
morally  superior  to  the  purely  '  passionate '  agent, 
being  given  identical  data  of  action.  I  think  it  is 
doubtful." 

Contemporary  disciples  f  of  Kant  have  recognised 
that  "  passion  is  part  of  a  man's  nature  ";2  that  there 
are  sentiments  (such  as  love)  which  may  be  approved 
by  reason ;  and  finally,  that  "  the  general  agreement 
between  sentiment  and  reason  is  complete "  in  the 
conception  of  a  really  human  ideal.  "  Every  thesis 
which  definitively  separates  the  elements  of  human 
nature  is  erroneous.  Man  is  an  order,  a  harmony  of 
reciprocally  conditioned  and  therefore  inseparable 
functions." 

The  occasionally  dramatic  character  of  deliberation 
is  due  to  the  conflict  of  different  tendencies.  The 

1  Science  de  la  Morale,  p.  185.  2  Renouvier,  ibid. 

5 


66  THE    MORAL    WILL. 

opposition  of  the  vilest  and  the  most  generous  pas- 
sions, or  the  grossest  appetites  and  the  loftiest 
inclinations,  compels  the  mind  of  the  moral  agent 
to  pass  through  peculiarly  exciting  alternatives 
when  it  is  a  question  of  critical  determinations. 
The  more  a  mind  is  developed,  the  more  numerous 
are  the  tendencies  which  a  practical  conception 
"awakens,  and  associates  itself  with  for  the  purpose 
of  strengthening  or  weakening  itself,"  if  one  may  use 
such  expressions,  considering  the  ideas  as  capable 
of  attraction  -or  repulsion,  and  of  association  with 
the  emotions,  the  inclinations,  the  desires,  etc.  In 
reality  it  is  the  personal  consciousness  which  be- 
comes this  or  that,  which  successively  admits 
according  to  its  law  of  evolution,  according  to  its 
fundamental  nature,  sometimes  one  tendency,  some- 
times another,  this  in  turn  giving  place  to  a  third; 
while  others,  less  clearly  perceived  at  first,  approach 
the  point  of  apperception,  or  prepare  for  the  appear- 
ance of  another. 


35.  The  Conseious  Processes. 

The  conflict  is  not  so  much  a  struggle  between 
simultaneously  presented  elements,  as  a  succession  of 
facts  of  consciousness,  which  being  incapable  of 
simultaneous  presence  in  clear  consciousness,  must 
each  await  its  turn ;  so  that  each  first  appears 
victorious  over  all  the  others  only  to  be  im- 
mediately dethroned  by  its  successor. 

It  is  of  importance  on  this  point  to  destroy  a 
general  misconception,  due  to  the  metaphors  which 
are  used  in  the  ordinary  language  of  psychologists. 
They  present  deliberation  as  a  kind  of  progressive 


THE    CONSCIOUS    PROCESSES.  67 

accumulation,  in  the  two  scales  of  a  balance,  of 
weight  and  counterweight,  having  each  its  mental 
effect  just  as  the  metal  weights  have  each  the 
physical  effect  which  is  inherent  in  them.  Inclina- 
tions are  thus  transformed  into  things,  instead  of 
being  considered  as  simple,  fugitive  modifications 
of  an  essentially  unstable  subject,  necessarily  in 
process  of  change. 

In  reality,  in  deliberation  there  is  a  state  of  con- 
sciousness which  is  being  more  or  less  slowly 
elaborated,  which  will  be  complex  in  proportion  as 
the  states  of  anterior  consciousness  have  been  pro- 
gressively more  complex,  have  each  embraced  in  its 
synthetic  unity  an  ever-increasing  number  of  ends 
and  feelings.  The  practical  idea  gathers  like  a  snow- 
ball because  the  thought  develops,  being  maintained 
in  a  constant  direction  by  the  attention  accorded  at 
first  to  a  conception,  and  maintained  and  revived 
unceasingly  by  the  interest  the  conception  offers  from 
several  points  of  view'.1 

The  condition  of  attention,  as  we  have  seen,  is  that 
the  representations  are  as  concrete  as  possible,  and 
are  closely  connected  with  the  interests  of  the  indi- 
vidual, or  associated  with  the  characteristic  tendencies 
of  the  being.  Deliberation  is  therefore  the  natural 
consequence  of  an  interesting  conception.  If  the 
tendency  to  which  responds  the  practical  idea  which 
has  been  conceived  is  a  simple  tendency,  exclusive  of 
any  other — a  passion  or  an  appetite  which  demands 
to  be  satisfied  without  our  being  able  to  oppose  it  by 
another  sentiment, — then  deliberation  is  immediately 
concluded.  If  the  direction  taken  by  the  mind  is 
less  unilinear,  if  the  attention  is  attracted  in  different 

1  Cf.  James,  op.  cit.,  ii.  528.— TR. 


68  THE    MORAL   WILL. 

directions,  thanks  to  the  intrusion  of  different  inte- 
rests, then  deliberation  lasts  until  the  oscillations  of 
the  attention  cease.1  In  the  animal  the  attention  is 
especially  unilinear,  and  that  is  why  in  the  conduct 
towards  man  of  the  inferior  beings  there  is  no 
important  modification  or  prolonged  hesitation;  the 
appetite  of  the  animal  carries  it  at  once  by  the 
shortest  and-  the  easiest  way,  and  therefore  most 
often  by  hereditary  means,  to  realisation  or  ends 
which  are  always  the  same,  or  vary  but  little  from 
generation  to  generation.  During  three-quarters  of 
his  existence  man  is  no  doubt  purely  and  simply  an 
animal;  instead  of  reasoning  he  is  often  content  to 
infer;  instead  of  willing  he  repeats  and  imitates; 
instead  of  discussing  he  obeys;  and  there  is  no 
greater  tyranny  than  that  of  habits  of  mind  fortified 
by  collective  custom,  fashion,  and  social  constraint, 
to  which,  as  we  shall  see  farther  on,  we  give  way 
unconsciously,  and  which  dictate  in  many  cases  our 
conduct,  pointing  out  the  means  and  the  ends. 

36.  Irreflection  and  Good  Manners. 

The  distinction  between  manners  and  morality 
depends  entirely  on  the  fact  that  we  may  have  good 
manners  according  to  the  environment  in  which  we 
live  without  having  real  morality,  and  unmoral  good 
manners  are  created  the  more  easily  in  proportion  as 
we  are  the  slaves  of  custom,  tradition,  the  require- 
ments of  our  age,  country,  caste,  or  city,  and  in 
proportion  as  we  live  mechanically,  the  sport  of 
exterior  influences. 

To  examine  human  nature  from  the  point  of  view 

1  James,  op.  at.,  ii.  529. — TR. 


IRREFLECTION    AND    GOOD    MANNERS.  69 

of  the  action  which  is  most  in  conformity  with  that 
nature  itself,  taken  in  all  its  complexity,  we  can  con- 
ceive of  a  mode  of  determination  superior  to  that  of  so 
many  people  \vho  have  only  good  manners,  who  only 
choose  in  reality  what  others  have  chosen  for  them, 
and  only  approve  of  what  is  approved  in  their  own 
environment,  etc.  People  of  this  type  never  expe- 
rience the  feeling,  almost  approaching  anguish,1 
which  is  not  infrequent  in  the  being  who  meditates, 
sees  the  inconveniences  and  the  advantages,  and 
has  to  decide  in  spite  of  his  doubts,  in  spite  of 
apprehensions  wrhich  are  often  stronger  in  pro- 
portion to  the  length  and  the  conscientiousness  of 
his  reflection. 

Such  a  man  has  evidently  used  a  human  privilege ; 
some  may  say  that  it  is  a  melancholy  privilege ;  human 
nature  has  what  are  obviously  defects,  but  defects  to 
which  its  greatness  when  compared  to  animal  nature 
is  due.  If  the  beasts  have  instinct  with  its  relative 
certainty  and  invariability,  they  have  not  the  merit 
of  a  voluntary  decision  which  is  sometimes  painful, 
and  sometimes  unfortunate,  in  spite  of  good  inten- 
tions, but  wiiich  is  still  a  decision  alone  worthy  of  a 
being  who  aspires  to  self-guidance. 

Facts  show  that  most  men,  and  especially  those 
whom  the  majority  consider  as  the  best  representa- 
tives of  the  human  race,  believe  that  the  superiority 
of  man  over  the  other  animals  springs  from  that 
multilinear  attention  which  M.  Ribot  distinguishes 
from  animal  attention  by  calling  the  one  spontaneous 
and  the  other  voluntary.  It  is  therefore  agreed  that 
in  the  present  conditions  of  human  existence  we 

x    Video  ineliora.  proboqite,    dcteriora   sequor. — OVID,    Metani.^  vii. 
20.— TR. 


70  THE    MORAL   WILL. 

must  attribute  the  greatest  importance  to  the  diver- 
sities of  the  tendencies  in  deliberation. 

37.  The  Choice  of  the  Best. 

Now  when  a  man  deliberates  on  the  investment  of 
his  fortune, — if  he  chooses,  for  instance,  to  build  a 
comfortable  house  rather  than  to  invest  his  money 
in  the  funds  or  in  property, — what  determines  his 
choice  is  the  desire  to  satisfy  the  tendency  which  he 
thinks  the  best.  It  would  be  absurd  for  him  to  satisfy 
himself  by  the  gratification  of  a  desire  or  of  an  appetite 
of  which  he  disapproved ;  it  would  be  at  once  self- 
approval  and  self-disapproval  to  consider  a  tendency 
as  evil  and  to  act  as  if  it  were  good.  No  doubt  a 
man  may  openly  disapprove  with  his  lips,  and  yet  at 
the  bottom  of  his  heart  approve  of  one  and  the  same 
tendency,  and  all  the  time  be  acting  quite  bond 
fide;  for  not  infrequently  are  we  led  by  our 
reasoning  to  conclusions  which  we  do  not  trust, 
and  which  we  formulate  without  conviction,  under 
the  influence  of  a  logic  which  is  that  of  the  lan- 
guage and  the  mind,  but  at  which  the  passion 
that,  in  spite  of  all  cavil,  possesses  us,  is  moved 
to  mirth. 

What  is  impossible,  and  Socrates1  clearly  saw  this, 
is  that  we  should  know  one  thing  to  be  good  and 
proclaim  another  to  be  bad,  sincerely  and  from  the 
bottom  of  our  hearts,  and  yet  in  spite  of  this  that 
we  should  choose  the  latter.  For  that  to  be  so, 
according  to  Aristotle,2  we  can  only  have  a  general 
recognition  of  good  and  evil,  and  we  must  blunder 
in  our  reasoning  in  passing  from  the  general  to  the 
particular. 

1  Meno,  77.--TR.  -  Cf.  Ethics,  Book  III.,  chaps,  i.-v.— TR. 


PRIORITY   OF   THE    TENDENCY    OVER   THE    IDEA.    71 

Now  the  good,  from  the  point  of  view  of  the 
psychologist,  is  simply  the  object  of  a  desire,  of  a 
tendency.  The  idea  of  the  good  is  only  universal 
because  the  tendency  is,  every  tendency  responding 
to  the  category  of  end.  Tendencies  differ,  and  so  do  the 
different  forms  of  the  good  ;  and  just  as  certain  tend- 
encies conflict  and  others  overlap,  so  there  are 
irreconcilable  forms  of  the  good,  and  forms  of  the 
good  which  serve  as  means  to  the  realisation  of 
higher  forms.  The  conflict  between  tendencies 
corresponds  to  a  definitive  or  transient  opposition  of 
ends  or  forms  of  good. 


38.  Priority  of  the  Tendency  over  the  Idea  of 
the  Good. 

But  is  it  the  end  which  determines  the  tendency, 
or  is  it  the  tendency  we  have  experienced  which 
makes  us  conceive  of  certain  ends  and  forms  of  good  ? 
This  is  the  question  recently  asked  by  the  physio- 
logical psychologists,  as  they  are  sometimes  called  in 
opposition  to  the  psychologists  of  the  intellectualistic 
school.  To  the  former  it  is  the  outlined  movement 
which  by  its  direction  reveals  the  end  to  which  the 
vital  processus  tends ;  by  taking  into  account  the 
biological  modifications  and  their  object  we  acquire 
the  psychological  notion  of  tendency.  Natural 
adaptation  is  therefore  anterior  to  conscious  finality, 
just  as  movement  is  to  intention,  or  the  reflex  action 
to  the  voluntary  act. 

It  follows  that  we  are  not  conscious  of  all  the 
tendencies  of  our  being,  of  the  appetites  which 
govern  us  and  determine  us  without  our  knowledge, 
and  which  combine  we  know  not  how.  We  outline 


72  THE    MORAL  WILL. 

our  movements,  and  we  are  not  the  masters  of  these 
outlines  of  action.  Their  fundamental  determinism 
causes  the  determinism  of  our  voluntary  deliberations. 
This  determinism  of  psychic  by  biological  facts,  and 
this  subordination  of  conscious  tendencies  to  uncon- 
scious appetites,  are  of  the  utmost  importance  in  the 
examination  of  deliberation  and  of  voluntary  choice, 
especially  when  that  choice  is  moral.  If  the  good  is 
the  aim  of  the  tendency  (instead  of  determining  the 
tendency  itself,  as  most  philosophers  and  moralists 
suppose),  each  will  conceive  the  supreme  good 
according  to  his  predominant  -tendency,  and  this 
tendency  will  triumph  over  the  others  in  energy  and 
constancy,  not  by  a  free  act,  not  in  virtue  of  an  inex- 
plicable decision  of  the  mysterious  will,  but  in  virtue 
of  that  biological  determinism  which  is  expressed  by 
the  word  "  temperament  "  or  "  character." 

39.  Moral  Subjectivism. 

Hence,  each  will  conceive  the  good  in  his  own  way, 
according  to  his  psycho-physiological  nature,  and 
will  be  led  by  that  nature  to  one  choice  rather  than 
to  another,  since  in  the  succession  of  phenomena 
of  which  deliberation  is  composed,  the  tendencies 
appear  each  in  its  turn,  and  all  save  one  disappear, 
whether  they  are  eliminated  altogether  or  blended 
with  that  which  persists,  uniting  with  it  in  order 
to  definitively  fix  the  attention.  Undoubtedly  this 
scientific  datum,  if  exact  and  exclusive  of  every  other 
datum  more  favourable  to  morality,  runs  the  risk  of 
inducing  us  to  abandon  purely  and  simply  every 
attempt  to  exercise  by  theories,  discourses,  or  exhor- 
tations, any  influence  whatever  on  the  determinations 


UNIFICATION    OF   TENDENCIES    AND    HEREDITY.    73 

of  our  fellows.  Those  alone  can  be  convinced  of  the 
excellence  of  a  form  of  good,  whose  tendencies  are 
orientated  and  hierarchised  in  the  direction  of  that 
good ;  those  who  have  an  ardent  and  passionate  tem- 
perament will  necessarily  adopt  a  hedonist  morality; 
those  whose  temperament  is  cold  will  only  compre- 
hend a  utilitarian  morality;  in  short,  we  must  adapt 
moral  theories  to  the  different  temperaments,  and 
not  try  to  subject  all  types  of  man  to  a  single 
rule. 

But  the  scope  of  individual  differences  must  not  be 
exaggerated;  in  many  cases  human  solidarity  has 
the  same  effect  as  animal  instinct  with  its  uniformity 
and  specific  character.1 

40.   Unification  of  Tendencies  and  Heredity. 

This  solidarity  has  a  twofold  psychological  founda- 
tion— sympathy  and  heredity.  Sympathy  is  the 
mark  of  an  aptitude,  as  it  were,  to  put  oneself  in  unison 
with  others,  especially  from  the  emotional  point  of 
view.  Such  an  aptitude  allowrs  of  the  ready  propaga- 
tion, in  the  crowd,  of  the  emotions,  tendencies,  and 
sentiments  of  a  few  individuals.  It  is  the  cause  of 
spontaneous  imitation,  alogical,  and  sometimes  illo- 
gical, and  M.  Tarde2  has  shown  us  how  important 
this  imitation  is  from  the  point  of  view  of  morals. 
It  creates  collective  sentiments,  emotions,  and  tend- 
encies, sometimes  so  violent  that,  like  individual 
passions,  they  tend  to  destroy  all  that  is  opposed  to 
their  development ;  ipso  facto  it  is  the  principle  of 
social  constraint.  Men  in  more  or  less  numbers, 

1  Cf.  Guyau,  Education  and  Heredity  (Walter  Scott),  pp.  82,  83.— TK. 
-  Les  Lois  de  r Imitation,  pp.  158-212,  and  passim. — TK. 


74  THE    MORAL   WILL. 

united  by  a  solidarity  of  sentiment  and  therefore  of 
interest,  will  always  try  to  impose  on  individuals 
their  manner  of  seeing  and  feeling  ;  and  they  will 
only  discover  that  they  can  not  attain  their  object 
of  imposing  it  on  most  isolated  minds  by  a  constant 
repetition  of  the  same  acts,  inducing  a  habit,  more 
and  more  inhibitive  to  unfavourable  reactions. 

The  result  is  that  men  living  in  society  (and  how 
can  they  live  otherwise  ?)  have  with  few  excep- 
tions mutual  solidarity  in  good  as  well  as  evil,  and 
are  incapable  of  isolating  themselves  to  live  each 
according  to  his  own  caprice,  and  according  to  an 
original  conception.  The  "  gregarious  instinct " 
created  the  primitive  solidarity,  that  of  animals, 
which  M.  Durkheim  calls  "  mechanical  solidarity."1 
Now  the  gregarious  instinct  is  simply  the  result  of 
sympathy,  of  moral  contagion,  of  the  constraint 
naturally  exercised  on  the  individual  by  collectivity. 
As  soon  as  he  became  conscious  of  this  instinct,  man 
caused  it  to  disappear  as  far  as  its  form  is  concerned ; 
but  he  could  not  destroy  its  causes,  and  therefore  the 
most  important  of  these  causes  still  subsist.  All 
society  tends  to  uniformity  of  manners  through  uni- 
formity of  emotions,  tendencies,  and  sentiments. 
This  acquired  uniformity  is  made  hereditary  by  the 
individual  or  social  transmission  of  aptitudes.  The 
power  of  tradition  cannot  be  gainsaid.  The  family 
forms  a  complete  solidarity  of  several  successive 
generations ;  the  same  spirit  animates  its  different 
members,  characters  are  brought  into  harmony,  and 
just  as  one  might  give  a  generic  image  of  the  in- 
dividuals who  compose  the  family  aggregate,  so  one 
might  discover  their  common  character  from  the 

1  Op.  cit.t  pp.  73-117.— TR. 


UNIFICATION    OF   TENDENCIES   AND    HEREDITY.    75 

point  of  view  of  manners,  sentiments,  modes  of 
emotional  reaction  and  of  appetition. 

In  the  city  as  in  the  family,  in  the  state  as  in 
the  city,  in  the  race  as  in  the  state,  although  with 
diminishing  force,  may  be  manifested  in  the  same 
way  the  solidarity  of  successive  generations,  the 
more  recent  inheriting  their  prejudices  and  inclina- 
tions from  their  predecessors. 

We  must  therefore  add  to  the  immediate  influence 
of  imitation  the  repeated  influences  which  are  exer- 
cised on  ancestral  consciousness,  and  which  have 
contributed  to  the  birth  of  hereditary  tendencies 
favourable  to  some  modes  of  conduct  and  unfavour- 
able to  others.  If  it  is  safer  not  to  assert  the 
hereditary  transmission  of  more  or  less  complex 
ideas,  of  conceptions  as  comprehensive  as  those  of 
a  certain  moral  good,  we  may  believe  in  the  trans- 
mission of  certain  appetitions  and  repulsions  which 
are  created  by  the  contact  of  mind  and  experience, 
and  which  then  determine  a  series  of  acts  and  a  sum- 
total  of  habits,  in  some  measure  instinctive,  of  which 
it  would  be  difficult  for  the  agent  to  explain  the 
origin  and  the  formation.  These  tendencies,  which 
rise  one  knows  not  whence,  possess  an  imperious 
character  which  can  very  often  convert  into 
categorical  imperatives  precepts  which  at  first  were 
technical  rules  or  counsels  of  prudence,  or  simple 
forms  of  obedience  to  the  collective  will.  The  in- 
dividual who  feels  rising  within  him  in  this  way 
sentiments  of  obligation  of  which  he  does  not  know 
the  psycho-physiological  source,  is  naturally  prone  to 
believe  that  he  hears  "  the  voice  of  conscience,"  and 
that  he  is  benefiting  by  a  "  revelation  of  duty." 

Very  often  a  man  has  a  noble  or  a  mean  soul  be- 


76  THE    MORAL   WILL. 

cause  he  is  hereditarily  predisposed  to  independence 
of  mind  and  to  freedom,  or  to  docility,  humility,  and 
obedience,  by  the  aptitude  and  manner  of  action  of 
several  preceding  generations.  We  then  feel  it  our 
duty  either  to  revolt  against  tyranny,  or  to  assist  the 
weak,  or  to  abstain  from  every  form  of  cupidity  or 
meanness,  or,  on  the  other  hand,  we  are  disposed  to 
submission,  compliance,  or  vengeance. 

We  have  discussed  the  individual  determinism  due 
to  the  influence  which  is  exercised  by  the  peculiar 
temperament  and  character  of  each  being  on  his 
tendencies  and  his  decisions.  We  now  see  another 
determinism,  that  which  springs  from  the  influence 
exercised  on  the  individual  by  the  social  environ- 
ment in  which  he  lives,  and  in  which  his  ancestors 
have  lived,  an  influence  which  tends  to  nothing  less 
than  to  make  him  as  like  as  possible  to  his  fellow- 
men.  These  two  determinisms  are  therefore  in 
conflict,  unless  the  former  becomes  continuous 
with  the  latter,  owing  to  the  simple  fact  that 
the  individual  temperament  and  character  are 
almost  entirely  formed  by  the  environment  and  by 
heredity. 

Whether  the  individual  tendencies  are  in  harmony 
or  in  disagreement  with  the  collective,  the  latter 
are  none  the  less  important  factors,  though  very  often 
ignored,  of  voluntary  deliberation.  In  spite  of  our- 
selves we  are  the  product  of  our  age,  country,  and 
race ;  and,  however  keen  may  be  the  desire  to  be 
singular,  even  if  we  wished  to  push  originality  to  the 
verge  of  the  bizarre  and  the  eccentric,  we  cannot 
succeed,  so  deeply  are  we  impregnated,  so  to  speak, 
by  the  collective  spirit. 

Here,    then,    is    the     principal    obstacle    to    the 


THE    REASON.  77 

establishment  of  a  morality  which  has  already  been 
successfully  attacked ;  the  fundamental  sociability 
of  man  is  opposed  to  each  having  his  own  concep- 
tion of  the  good  and  of  practical  tendencies,  a 
conception  radically  different  from  that  of  his 
contemporaries. 

41.  The  Reason. 

But  \ve  have,  so  far,  omitted  to  remember  that 
man  is  a  reasonable  animal,  and  that  in  addition 
to  his  animal  appetites  —  assuredly  born  of  un- 
conscious appetitions  of  the  different  elements  of 
his  being,  such  as  the  appetite  for  food  or  the 
sexual  appetite — he  possesses  tendencies  to  intel- 
lectual life,  such  as  are  afforded  by  study,  medita- 
tion, the  contemplation  of  beauty,  etc.  The  most 
empirical  psychology  may  recognise  that  man 
experiences  pleasure  in  thinking,  acting,  and  reason- 
ing in  a  rational  manner.  These  tendencies,  no 
doubt,  do  not  come  to  him  from  the  organism ; 
this  pleasure  is  not  so  clearly  psycho  -  physiological 
as  the  other  emotions;  but  it  is  none  the  less  true 
that  certain  savants  have  had  the  passion  for  truth, 
a  passion  which  has  proved  the  dominant  rule  of 
their  lives,  and  that  other  men — artists,  dilettanti, 
and  "believers"  —have  had  a  lasting  and  fruitful 
passion  for  the  beautiful,  and  for  the  rationally 
conceived  ideal. 

We  must  therefore  recognise  that  the  desire  of 
living  the  rational  life,  so  far  from  not  being  clearly 
preponderant  in  all  men,  is  nevertheless  almost  uni- 
versal, and  that,  as  Spinoza  said,1  the  love  of  reason 

1  Cf.  Guyau,  La  Morale  d' Epicure >  Hi.  pp.  235,  236.—  Tiu 


78  THE    MORAL   WILL. 

is  of  all  human  tendencies  the  most  capable  of 
bringing  us  into  agreement. 

We  may  preach  to  our  fellows  the  love  of  reason 
without  the  fear  that  their  different  temperaments 
will  lead  them  to  turn  a  deaf  ear  to  us.  Even  the 
most  passionate  almost  always  wish  to  act  reason- 
ably, and  try  to  understand  and  to  make  their  action 
and  their  choice  understood  by  indicating  the  why 
and  the  wherefore. 

If  the  animal  could  be  questioned  as  to  his  acts 
and  his  motives  he  could  only  argue  from  the  act 
that  he  necessarily  conceives,  and  that  his  nature 
causes  him  to  conceive;  man  questioned  in  the 
same  way,  seeks  as  a  rule  the  reason  of  his  choice 
in  a  perfectly  human  motive,  the  desire  for  systematic 
action,1  and  he  recognises  that  he  is  only  wrong 
when  it  is  proved  to  him  either  that  his  conduct 
is  not  coherent  or  that  his  choice  lacks  rationality. 

It  is  because  reflection  on  his  own  nature  can  give 
to  man  these  tendencies  that  pure  physiology  will 
never  explain  them,  or  will  only  explain  them  im- 
perfectly. Finding  that  he  can  learn,  man  tries  to 
analyse  these  processes  of  his  knowledge ;  he  rises  to 
the  idea  of  necessity  or  law,  and  from  that  moment 
he  seeks  around  him  what  is  necessary — obedience  to 
the  law.  Necessity  implies  universality.  The  law 
is  theoretical  or  practical. 

When  it  is  practical,  it  is  called  the  rule  of 
universal  conduct,  and  thus  the  love  of  reason 
involves  respect  for  the  moral  law.  Kant's  psycho- 
logy was  correct  when  he  imagined  that  he  saw 
this  sentiment,  which  is  the  motive  of  the  noblest 
human  actions,  involved  in  what  is  generally  called 

1  Vide  Section  19. 


THE    UNION    OF   TENDENCIES    AND    OF    REASON.    79 

"good  will."  That  is  certainly  a  great  psychological 
truth.  Man  has  a  very  strong  tendency  to  act  from 
good  will — that  is  to  say,  out  of  respect  for  a  rational 
rule.  This  tendency  may  counterbalance  the  effect 
of  many  others,  and,  in  a  large  measure,  may  con- 
tribute to  the  final  decision. 


42.  The  Union  of  Different  Tendencies  and 
of  Reason. 

The  desire  of  acting  rationally  cannot  always  be 
in  itself  alone  the  determinant  motive  of  voluntary 
action ;  it  must  be  united  to  others  having  a  more 
concrete  and  therefore  more  attractive  object  than 
reason.  Intellectual  desire  only  acts  energetically 
on  the  human  mind  w7hen  it  is  united  to  appetites 
and  desires  which  have  their  roots  in  the  depths  of 
our  psycho-physiological  being.  Is  such  an  alliance 
possible  ?  Kant  did  not  doubt  it,  because  he  believed 
that  you  will  never  meet  with  a  man  who  has  acted 
through  pure  respect  for  the  moral  law  and  from 
practical  pure  reason.  And  further,  every  kind  of 
sentiment  may  present  in  its  totality  a  rational 
character,  for  the  desire  of  realising  a  system,  far 
from  excluding  different  tendencies,  implies  on  the 
contrary  tendencies  as  varied  as  possible. 

Thus  we  find  what  we  thought  we  had  lost 
in  the  course  of  our  psychological  analysis :  the 
possibility  of  acting  on  others  by  moral  theories, 
the  faculty  that  men  have  of  a  mutual  agree- 
ment to  adopt  a  rule  or  a  collection  of  common 
rules  of  conduct,  which  are  objective,  imposing 
themselves  on  all  in  the  name  of  a  power  revered 
by  all,  a  power  which  is  no  more  exterior  than 


8o  LIBERTY    AND    MORALITY. 

interior,  and  which  rather  is  immanent  in  each  of  us, 
only  compelling  us  to  act  by  means  of  the  influence 
which  we  attribute  to  it. 

But  being  reasonable  by  nature,  as  by  nature  we 
are  led  to  the  satisfaction  of  numerous  appetites,  we 
become  more  or  less  reasonable  as  we  become  more 
or  less  impulsive,  according  to  the  education  we  have 
received,  our  environment,  our  circumstances,  and  the 
physical,  biological,  and  sociological  influences  to 
which  we  are  exposed.  Thus  we  are  sometimes  more 
and  sometimes  less  disposed  to  act  rationally.  There 
are  ethical  civilisations  and  hedonistic  civilisations; 
others,  again,  are  utilitarian,  and  others  idealist — 
civilisations  of  every  kind,  some  more  and  some  less 
suited  to  the  development  of  those  higher  tendencies 
which  are  characteristic  of  human  nature. 

In  short,  tendencies,  whether  hereditary  or  ac- 
quired, whether  part  and  parcel  of  our  character 
or  preponderant  but  for  the  moment  (and  in  these 
we  include  rational  tendencies),  seem,  so  far,  to  be 
the  only  determinant  causes  of  our  moral  volitions 
as  much  by  the  influence  that  they  exercise  on  con- 
ception and  deliberation,  as  by  the  choice  which 
they  involve. 

II. 

LIBERTY  AND   MORALITY. 
43.  Kant  and  Free  Will. 

What  becomes  of  liberty  in  the  presence  of  so 
much  determinism  ?  We  know  what  importance 
the  affirmation  or  negation  of  "free  will"  has 


KANT    AND    FREE    WILL.  8l 

assumed  in  moral  theories.  Kant  admitted  as 
necessary  "the  supposition  of  independence  with 
respect  to  the  world  of  the  senses,  and  that  of  the 
existence  of  a  faculty  to  determine  one's  own  will 
according  to  the  law  of  the  intelligible  w^orld,"1  or,  to 
put  it  in  another  way,  "  the  causality  of  a  being  in  so 
far  as  he  belongs  to  the  intelligible  world;"2  but  he 
did  not  believe  in  the  free  causality  of  a  phenomenal 
being;  in  the  world  of  phenomena  he  saw  nothing 
but  determinism. 

In  the  sensible  sphere,  which  alone  is  of  interest 
to  positivists  and  phenomenists  as  the  only  one  that 
we  can  know,  Kant  was  content  with  respect  for 
the  law  of  duty  as  the  sole  motive  which  must 
determine  virtuous  actions.  He  then  gives  us  the 
example  of  a  moralist  who,  outside  the  metaphysical 
considerations  by  which  he  is  otherwise  attracted,  is 
content  with  a  determinism  in  which  he  brings  in  on 
good  grounds  as  the  principle  of  determination,  the 
tendency  to  act  according  to  reason. 

The  affirmation  of  noumenal  liberty  neither  hinders 
nor  aids  any  one.  In  no  w^ay  does  it  hinder  those 
who  have  rejected  the  belief  in  the  noumenon,  those 
wrho  consider  the  substance  of  the  metaphysician  as 
an  accursed  idol;  it  in  no  w7ay  assists  those  wrho 
believe  in  the  existence  behind  phenomena  of  a  "thing 
in  itself,"  of  which  we  can  know  nothing,  and  which 
can  only  intervene  in  the  positive  order  by  taking  a 
sensible  form.  The  hypothesis  of  noumenal  liberty 
is  only  definitely  used  in  Kant's  doctrine  to  affirm 
the  existence  of  a  character  which  is  proper  to  each 
phenomenal  being.  The  being  in  himself  having 
freely  decided  to  take  this  or  that  character,  the 

1  Critique  of  Practical  Reason.  *  Ibid. 


82  LIBERTY   AND    MORALITY. 

sensible  man  has  the  corresponding  character.  To 
us  who  know  how  many  different  factors  concur  in 
the  formation  of  our  character,  the  Kantian  hypo- 
thesis is  hardly  anything  but  a  confession  of  psycho- 
logical and  sociological  ignorance:  the  philosopher 
of  Koenigsberg  himself,  ignoring  the  laws  of  in- 
dividual and  social  heredity,  and  of  solidarity  in  time 
and  space,  thought  he  was  laying  down  the  really 
primal  term  when  he  chose  the  individual  character. 

44.  The  Origin  of  Character. 

Can  it  be  said  that  this  was  a  total  mistake  ?  We 
do  not  know  the  factors  of  our  principal  tendencies 
and  principal  habits;  but  will  not  one  point  always 
remain  in  obscurity — the  radical  origin  of  our  ego  ? 

At  what  moment  do  we  begin  a  distinct  existence  ? 

If  we  admit  that  the  first  moment  is  the  dividing 
up,  the  bipartition,  for  instance,  of  a  cell  till  then 
single,  from  that  moment  the  being  has  its  own 
peculiar  orientation,  which  differs  very  little  it  may 
be  from  the  orientation  of  the  neighbouring  cell;  it 
manifests  attractions  and  repulsions  which  are  not 
those  of  the  relatively  simple  beings  which  surround 
it.  It  has  already  its  ow7n  character,  which  will  exer- 
cise an  influence  on  its  own  evolution,  which  is  already 
the  "  directing  idea  of  the  organism  "  of  which  Claude 
Bernard  speaks.  External  stimuli  will  no  doubt 
provoke  reactions  which,  as  they  become  habitual, 
will  give  rise  to  tendencies,  or  at  least  to  acquired 
appetitions  and  repulsions,  which  will  combine  with 
each  other  and  with  fresh  appetitions  and  primitive 
repulsions  to  constitute  a  more  and  more  complex 
character;  but  every  reaction  of  a  given  subject  is  a 


THE    ORIGIN    OF   CHARACTER.  83 

function  of  that  subject,  and  bears  the  mark  of  the 
peculiar  nature  of  that  subject;  so  that  to  discover  the 
external  causes  of  such  and  such  a  character  does  not 
dispense  with  the  necessity  of  discovering  the  matter 
on  which  these  causes  are  exercised.  It  is  this 
primal  matter  which  may  be  considered  as  a 
radical  irreducible  fact.  For  to  say  that  an  or- 
ganised being  has  had  as  its  origin  the  bipartition 
of  a  cell  does  not  yet  suffice  as  the  full  reason  of  its 
appearance  in  nature.  Was  the  mother-cell  a  simple 
unity?  Did  it  not  comprise  under  its  envelope 
different  elements  or  groups  of  elements  already 
orientated  in  a  different  manner  ?  And  who  can 
ever  tell  us  the  origin  of  the  natural  elements  ? 

If  we  got  so  far  as  to  show  how  nature  forms  with 
inorganic  elements  the  simplest  organic  compounds, 
if  we  were  to  discover  in  physico-chemical  combina- 
tions the  principle  ,of  life,  of  biological  and  psycho- 
logical organisations,  we  could  then  claim  to  give 
a  reason  for  the  characteristic  appetition  of  this  or 
that  embryo,  from  the  number  and  the  disposition  of 
its  molecules  and  atoms;  and  we  could  then  go  back 
to  the  source  of  the  radical  diversity  of  characters. 
But  the  distinction  between  the  organic  and  the  in- 
organic ever  tends  to  be  effaced,  not  so  much  by  the 
reduction  of  properties  vital  to  the  mechanism,  as  by 
the  identification  of  chemical  affinities  with  vital 
properties ;  the  domain  of  life  seems  to  be  as  wide  as 
the  domain  of  nature.  "  Life,"  says  Claude  Ber- 
nard,1 "  is  creation.  .  .  .  The  organising  synthesis 
remains  internal  and  silent.  ,  .  .  Vital  destruction 
is  only  comparable  to  a  large  number  of  physico- 
chemical  affinities  of  decomposition  and  subdivision." 

1  Lecons  stir  les  phenoinlnes  de  ia  vie,  pp.  39,  40. 


84  LIBERTY   AND    MORALITY. 

Would  not  therefore  the  hypothesis  be  too  bold  were 
we  to  assume  the  reduction  of  living  organism  to  even 
a  considerable  number  of  physico-chemical  pheno- 
mena, such  at  least  as  those  we  are  familiar  with  ? 


45.  Science,  Conscience,  and  Liberty. 

The  first  principle  of  each  individual  character 
therefore  remains  mysterious.  Is  that  a  sufficient 
reason  for  supposing  it  is  an  act  of  liberty?  The 
imagination  of  the  metaphysicians  could  rigorously 
lead  up  to  the  conception  of  a  soul  penetrating  the 
mother-cell,  we  know  not  how,  to  determine  its  bio- 
logical development  in  a  determinate  direction;  but 
such  a  supposition  without  a  basis  would  be  value- 
less and  unworthy  of  belief.  However,  a  mind,  an 
already  complex  consciousness,  only  appears  to  us 
susceptible  of  free  will,  if  we  understand  by  liberty 
not  the  simple  power  of  deviation,1  which  Epicurus 
recognised  in  atoms,  but  the  power  of  choosing  after 
deliberation,  and  of  making  a  choice  dictated  by 
reason. 

The  affirmation  of  free  will  is  therefore  rather  in 
conflict  than  in  harmony  with  the  data  of  science. 
Our  ignorance  of  the  first  commencement  of  every 
individual  existence  leaves  no  room  for  the  supposi- 
tion of  a  kind  of  primitive  "  clinamen,"  a  blind 
determination,  without  reason  or  moral  value. 

It  is  true  that  certain  contemporary  thinkers  have 
seemed  to  give  to  liberty,  and  therefore  to  the  dignity 
of  the  free  being,  a  place  apart  among  psychological 
facts,  by  asserting  liberty  to  be  "  an  immediate 

1  Lucretius,  ii.  292. — TR. 


SCIENCE,    CONSCIENCE,    AND    LIBERTY.  85 

datum  of  the  consciousness."1  They  have  thus 
revived  and  remarkably  strengthened  the  old  spiritual- 
istic thesis  of  liberty  affirmed  by  the  witness  of 
that  inner  sense,  to  which,  unfortunately,  we  cannot 
attach  much  importance,  for  it  hides  from  us  most 
psychic  facts,  and  only  lets  us  see  most  other  facts 
confusedly,  whatever  progress  introspection  may 
have  made.  They  have  carried  analysis  as  far  as 
possible,  in  order  to  destroy  the  illusion  that  the  first 
observation  of  ourselves  creates,  by  making  us  con- 
ceive of  our  states  of  consciousness  as  juxtaposed, 
and  of  the  elements  of  these  states  as  independent 
of  one  another,  acting  one  on  the  other  just  like 
weights,  or  any  other  mechanical  forces.  The  thesis 
of  determinism  has  thus  been  refuted  by  a  searching 
study  of  ourselves.  You  have  only  to  know  yourself 
well,  they  tell  us,  to  see  your  liberty.  Nothing  coulo^ 
prove  it  more  clearly  than  the  affirmation  of  a  philo- 
sophical conscience,  of  a  critical  spirit  which  has 
reached  a  very  high  degree  in  the  power  of  analysis, 
discovering  in  the  continuity  of  its  ego  and  of  its 
psychical  future  an  obstacle  impassable  by  all 
determinism. 

But  the  datum  of  the  consciousness  is  a  simple 
negation.  Let  us  admit  that  we  have  proved  that 
the  determinism  of  psychic  facts,  such  as  they  are 
usually  conceived,  does  not  exist.  It  is  not  estab- 
lished, inasmuch  as  each  being  from  his  birth  to  his 
death  is  endowed  with  an  autonomy  such  that  his 
liberty  is  inviolable  and  his  moral  dignity  incom- 
parable to  any  other  known  value.  Once  more  in 
this  interminable  dispute  between  the  partisans  and 

1  Cf.  Les  donnees  immediate*  de  la  conscience,  a  thesis  by  M.  Bergsen, 
an  eminent  professor  at  the  College  de  France.  Alcan,  1889. 


86  LIBERTY   AND    MORALITY. 

the  adversaries  of  liberty,  the  partisans  have  shown 
the  futility  of  certain  arguments  brought  forward  by 
their  adversaries  ;  but  the  discussion  is  far  from 
being  closed,  and  it  would  be  childish  to  proclaim 
metaphysic  liberty  as  an  indisputable  and  funda- 
mental fact. 


46.  Belief  and  Liberty. 

"  It  is  clear,"  says  M.  Renouvier,  speaking  of  the 
thesis  of  real  liberty,  "  that  I  ought  only  to  seek  for 
its  acceptation  by  belief  and  by  free  belief.  I  notice 
that  the  postulate  (of  liberty)  arising  out  of  and  not 
preceding  morality,  is  essentially  concerned  with 
other  doctrines  than  pure  morality.  .  .  This  postulate  is 
not  demanded  for  the  existence  of  morality.  .  .  What  is 
indispensable  to  morality  is  not  a  postulate,  it  is  a 
fact,  the  fact  of  liberty  that  is  apparent  and  practically 
believed,  and  from  which  no  one  can  escape  who 
deliberates  and  resolves  on  an  act,  comparing  dif- 
ferent possibilities  in  relation  to  the  good,  possibilities 
equally  practicable  according  to  his  practical  judg- 
ment, none  of  which  is  presented  to  him  beforehand 
as  obligatory." 

M.  Fouillee  goes  farther  in  the  same  direction.  He 
is  content  with  the  illusion  of  liberty.  He  believes 
that  although  real  liberty  may  fail  us,  the  idee-force 
of  liberty,  however  little  may  be  its  objective  value, 
will  render  us  the  greatest  services  from  the  moral 
point  of  view. 

1  An  idea-force  is  the  surplus  force  added  to  an  idea  by  the  factor 
of  its  reflection  in  consciousness.  Cf.  Fouillee,  IlEvohitionisme  des 
Idees-Forces,  Intro,  iv.,  "  Importance  de  la  question  des  Idees-Forces 
en  Morale,"  pp.  Ixvii-xciv. — TR. 


BELIEF   AND    LIBERTY.  87 

Thus  the  question  is  set  in  fresh  terms.  Is  the 
idea  of  liberty  necessary  to  moral  action  ?  This 
idea  cannot  be  that  of  an  indifferent  liberty, 
leaving  to  the  will  (a  mysterious  entity)  the  right 
of  pronouncing  arbitrarily,  and,  if  necessary,  in 
conflict  with  the  conclusions  of  reason,  with  pure 
indifference  to  all  ends  and  feelings.1  Such  a  liberty 
would  only  be  favourable  to  absurdity;  for  the  char- 
acteristic of  good  sense  and  judgment  is  that  it  gives 
the  reasons  of  things,  facts,  and  acts.  The  free  man 
par  excellence  would  be  the  man  who  could  give  the 
reason  of  none  of  his  voluntary  determinations,  who 
would  never  know  why  he  acts,  and  who,  like  certain 
insane  people,  persecuted  or  impulsive,  would  only 
feel  the  effects  of  a  force  which  urges  him,  leads  him, 
and  decides  in  him  and  for  him,  without  his  really 
taking  any  part  in  the  decision.  If  men  had  ever 
for  the  most  part  the  conviction  that  they  were  them- 
selves the  possessors  of  a  faculty  freed  from  all 
rational  control,  making  all  deliberation  and  all 
reasoning  useless,  would  not  the  result  be  horrible, 
and  should  we  not  see  a  kind  of  fatalism  arise,  based 
on  the  belief  in  a  Fatum  immanent  in  the  individual, 
replacing  the  "  destiny"  of  days  gone  by,  which  at 
any  rate  demanded  a  universe  and  took  the  place 
of  cosmic  law  ? 

The  idea  of  liberty  therefore  should  be  reconciled 
with  the  idea  of  determinism ;  but  then,  it  may  be 

1  "  Motifs  et  mobiles."  The  motij \irare  ideas  influencing  the  volition 
— are  intellectual.  Thus  a  motif  vs>  initiation  of  action  by  ideas  or  ends 
in  view.  The  mobiles  are  sentiments,  passions,  etc.,  influencing  the 
volition — i.e.,  are  emotional.  Thus  a  mobile  is  initiation  of  action  by 
feeing.  It  will  be  seen  that  it  is  difficult  to  find  simple  words  which 
will  adequately  express  the  meaning  of  motifs  and  mobiles. — TR. 


88  LIBERTY   AND    MORALITY. 

that  of  a  determination  by  oneself  opposed  to  that  of 
a  determination  by  a  power  outside  oneself,  of  an 
internal  opposed  to  an  external  causality.  The  idea 
of  a  free  man  is  that  of  an  agent  who  is  really  an 
agent  instead  of  being  simply  an  intermediary  for 
the  transmission  of  movements.  A  billiard  ball  is 
not  considered  free  because  it  receives  the  external 
impulse  which  in  its  turn  it  transmits;  but  some 
ordinary  minds  consider  that  animals  are  free  (the 
surest  indication  of  this  belief  is  that,  as  a  rule, 
they  impute  to  animals  misconduct,  and  strike  them 
and  ill-treat  them  as  if  they  were  responsible 
beings  capable  of  improvement),  because  an  animal 
appears  as  a  veritable  point  of  departure  of  move- 
ment, as  a  prime  motor,  capable  of  giving  rise,  to 
use  M.  Renouvier's  expression,  to  a  really  first 
beginning. 

Those  thinkers  who  refuse  liberty  to  the  animal 
grant  it  spontaneity,  and  reserve  the  name  of  liberty 
for  the  reasonable  spontaneity  of  man.  But  to  them 
a  mysterious  power  of  initiative  remains  the  essential 
thing  in  their  conception  of  free  will.  Now  psycho- 
logy, by  revealing,  as  I  think  I  have  shown  above, 
the  mechanism  of  deliberation  and  choice ;  the 
subordination  of  attention,  the  most  important  phe- 
nomenon of  all  in  voluntary  choice,  to  the  sensible 
appearance  of  different  and  more  and  more  powerful 
tendencies ;  the  formation  of  tendencies  and  their 
close  independence  with  respect  to  the  environment, 
to  heredity,  and  to  physico-chemical  and  biological 
phenomena;  will  not  psychology,  I  say,  faithful  to 
the  scientific  spirit,  crush  the  belief  in  this  power  of 
initiative,  in  this  idea  of  liberty,  and  crush  it  the 
more  easily  the  more  illusory  it  is  ? 


THE    PERSON,    THE    REAL   AGENT.  89 

It  may  be  objected  that  the  conscience  will  always 
protest  against  scientific  affirmation,  and  will  hold 
by  the  apparent  fact  of  liberty.  That  is  as  if  we 
were  to  say  that  the  conscience  will  always  protest 
against  such  a  scientific  assertion  as  that  the  earth 
moves  round  the  sun,  because  the  sensible  fact  is  the 
rotation  of  the  sun  round  the  earth.  The  most 
ignorant  man  in  the  civilised  nations  of  our  time 
knows  perfectly  well  that  it  is  the  earth  that  turns, 
and  if  he  had  in  some  action  to  take  account  of  the 
relations  of  the  earth  and  the  sun,  he  would  rather 
trust  the  scientific  assertion  than  the  sensible  datum. 

We  have  seen  that  although  science  has  not  yet 
succeeded  in  proving  the  absolute  determinism  of 
the  facts  of  consciousness,  it  hardly  leaves  any  place 
for  an  original  contingency.  Let  us  then  be  frank 
enough  to  say,  to  teach,  and  to  prove,  that  liberty, 
as  it  is  too  often  conceived,  is  an  illusion  due,  as 
Spinoza  foresaw,  to  ignorance  of  most  of  the  deter- 
mining causes  of  our  decisions. 

We  do  not  believe  in  the  virtue  of  illusory  ideas ; 
the  powder  of  an  illusion  can  in  every  case  be  only  of 
short  duration  ;  we  cannot  base  morality  on,  or  to 
say  the  least  support  it  by,  a  so-called  fact  which  has 
only  to  be  applied  to  secure  its  disappearance,  in  a 
great  measure  at  least,  because  it  includes  so  large 
a  share  of  error. 


47.  The  Person,  the  Real  Agent. 

Moreover,  truth  will  not  have  the  disastrous  con- 
sequences that  are  imagined.  Determinism,  properly 
understood,  does  not  compel  us  to  see  in  the  moral 
agent  a  simple  instrument,  or  a  simple  means  of 


go  LIBERTY   AND    MORALITY. 

transition  for  an  impulse  which  has  come  from  else- 
where. Every  organised  being  has  its  form,  which 
is  irreducible  to  another  form,  and  which  has  at  least 
as  much  importance  as  its  substance.  Individual 
properties  appear  with  the  appearance  of  life,  and 
so  do  action  and  reaction  according  to  the  nature 
peculiar  to  each  individual. 

We  must  also  avoid  an  error  that  is  common 
enough,  although  it  is  frequently  pointed  out :  that 
which  is  committed  whenever  we  consider  the  effect 
as  contained  in  the  cause.  To  positive  science  as 
well  as  to  the  phenomenist  philosophy,  cause  is  only 
the  antecedent  which  by  its  presence  or  by  its  relative 
position  determines  in  a  subject  certain  conse- 
quences, impels  a  subject  which  is  capable  of  action 
to  certain  well-determined  actions, — actions  which 
cannot  fail  to  be  identically  reproduced  under  the  same 
circumstances. 

Now,  when  it  is  a  question  of  a  living  being  which 
is  continually  changing,  the  effect  on  it  of  a  constant 
cause  is  also  changing,  and  in  the  proportion  in 
which  the  total  change  affects  the  relation  origin- 
ally existing  between  the  cause  and  the  part  or 
function  of  the  subject  specially  interested.  We  see, 
therefore,  that  in  a  living  being  the  same -causes  run 
a  considerable  risk  of  not  producing  the  same  effects 
at  different  times.  A  remedy  taken  now  cannot  have 
exactly  the  same  effect  as  if  it  had  been  taken  some 
week  ago ;  a  fortiori,  the  same  object  may  very  wrell 
fail  to  produce  on  me  to-morrow  the  same  explosion 
of  anger  wrhich  it  determines  to-day.  I  am  the  imme- 
diate cause,  in  the  scientific  and  philosophical  sense 
of  the  word,  of  this  change  of  causal  relation  ;  this  is 
because  my  ego  is  changing,  and  it  is  because  it 


THE  PERSON,  THE  REAL  AGENT.       QI 

is  following  out  its  own  peculiar  evolution  that  the 
effect  will  not  be  produced. 

The  living  being,  especially  the  reasonable  being 
who  reflects,  and  whose  reflection  still  more  compli- 
cates the  psychical  processes  by  introducing  into 
them  a  wider  share  of  personal  influences,  rightly 
therefore  considers  himself  as  an  agent,  as  a  cause 
endowed  with  a  peculiar  efficacy;  he  rightly  says 
that  he  is  not  determined  to  act  as  he  does  only  by 
what  is  external,  that  he  is  not  compelled  by  external 
forces;  that  he  is  a  bundle,  a  system  of  relatively 
independent  forces.  He  claims  that  he  is  competent 
to  choose  between  possibilities  the  field  of  which  is 
circumscribed  by  external  necessities ;  and  in  fact, 
a  certain  number  of  actions  remain  possible  until 
the  moment  when  deliberation,  attaining  its  "  term," 
makes  one  of  them  necessary.  No  doubt  the  factors 
of  this  deliberation  are  sentiments  and  tendencies ; 
but  they  are  his  sentiments  and  his  tendencies; 
they  are  he  in  short,  for  he  is  nothing  more  than  his 
psychic  states. 

Differences  of  opinion  on  liberty  spring  in  most 
cases  from  the  vicious  conception  of  the  ego,  which 
is  supposed  to  be  something  outside  the  ends  and 
feelings  which  then  seem  to  determine  it.  But  these 
tendencies,  these  representations  linked  by  reason- 
ings, which  are  the  ends  and  motives l  of  our  actions, 
these  are  we,  our  ego,  progressively  determining 
itself. 

To  sum  up,  although  the  evolution  of  the  acting 
agent,  the  ego,  is,  if  not  altogether,  at  least  in  a  great 
measure,  determined  by  external  causes,  yet  the  ego  is 
the  immediate  cause  of  its  voluntary  decisions  by  the 

1  Vide  footnote,  p.  87. 


g2  LIBERTY    AND    MORALITY. 

personal  and  original  future  which  is  quite  its  own, 
and  quite  irreducible  to  any  other  phenomena  of 
nature.  It  is  therefore  the  origin  of  a  new  causal 
series ;  if  we  cannot  give  from  other  sources  the  why  of 
its  nature,  at  least  we  can  give  the  why  of  its  acts. 
This  has  been  done  rather  than  that  because  I  was 
the  agent  and  no  one  else.  Could  I  prevent  myself 
from  doing  that  ?  The  question  is  the  same  as  if  I 
were  asked  if  I  could  not  be  what  I  was,  or  become 
other  than  I  was.  But  I  needed  an  anterior  or 
present  motive  to  be  other  than  I  am,  a  cause  of 
modification  in  my  future.  If  it  is  not  found  in  me, 
if  it  did  not  depend  on  me  at  the  instant  of  its 
birth,  if  it  could  not  depend  on  me  until  the  external 
aroused  it  in  my  mind,  I  have  been  what  I  could  be 
and  that  differs  from  what  I  might  be  now.  I  could 
not  therefore  say  why  my  deliberation  is  not  further 
prolonged ;  the  fact  is  that  it  has  been  checked  at 
a  certain  point,  because  /  have  not  pursued  my 
researches  farther,  or  in  another  direction. 

48.  Conclusion. 

Ethics  must,  therefore,  be  content  with  regarding 
the  being  as  a  real  moral  agent,  and  must,  therefore, 
set  itself  to  procure  for  men  at  the  moment  they  are  about 
to  take  a  decision,  as  many  ends  and  feelings  as  possible, 
so  as  to  make  deliberation  as  enlightened  as  possible. 

There  are  social  means  of  reinforcing  useful 
stimuli,  of  diminishing  the  influence  that  harmful 
stimuli  have  upon  a  mind  of  attracting  or  dis- 
tracting the  attention ;  there  is  an  individual  and 
collective  discipline  which  constitutes  the  moral 
education  of  the  child  and  of  the  adult,  and  which 
issues  in  deliberations  which  are  more  and  more 


CONCLUSION.  93 

fruitful  in  happy  choice.  To  prepare,  from  the 
tenderest  childhood,  the  ego  to  intervene  as 
representing  reason  in  the  breast  of  nature,  is  to 
prepare  man  for  freedom  with  respect  to  the 
individual  passions,  for  obedience  to  a  common 
law,  and  for  a  rational  rule  of  conduct ;  and  moral 
liberty  consists  in  such  a  freedom  and  in  such  an 
obedience. 

The  being  which  would  have  been  only  able  to  obey 
its  passions  is  thus  led  to  obey  the  rational  law.  Its 
cause  is  found  in  the  nature  of  the  man  who  allows, 
as  we  have  seen,  a  tendency  to  act  in  a  systematic 
manner,  to  think  according  to  reason,  and  to  give 
a  reason  for  acts  in  their  conformity  to  a  law. 
This  tendency  may  be  wreak  or  strong,  its  influence 
•may  be  slight  or  sovereign.  The  desire  to  strengthen 
it  has  always  been  the  intelligible  choice  of  a  certain 
number  of  individuals,  of  moralists;  and  they  are 
the  cause,  by  the  action  they  have  exercised  on  their 
fellows,  of  its  power  in  humanity,  of  the  place  that 
is  made  for  it  in  education,  and  therefore  of  the 
role  it  plays  in  the  intelligible  choice  made  by  moral 
beings1  (although  each  of  these  beings  may  be  the 
real  cause  of  his  choice).  And  therefore  morality, 
far  from  being  useless,  if  the  idea  of  liberty  does  not 
exist  as  most  moralists  and  philosophers  have  con- 
ceived it,  becomes,  on  the  contrary,  more  and  more 
useful  in  proportion  as  men  take  more  and  more 
account  of  the  determinism  of  their  actions,  and  of 

1  Thus  moral  liberty  appears  as  of  psycho-sociological  origin,  an 
aspect  under  which  it  has  never  yet  been  presented.  The  nearest 
approach  to  such  a  conception  would  be  the  idle-force  of  M.  Fouillee ; 
but  it  must  not  be  forgotten  that  it  is  definitively  but  the  illusion  of 
liberty,  as  long  as  the  social  evolution  which  we  here  indicate  is  real, 
and  has  a  cause  in  the  psychological  nature  of  man. 


94  THE    MORAL    TENDENCIES. 

the  necessity  of  each  becoming  an  "ego"  more 
complex,  more  rich  in  tendencies,  and,  in  particular, 
more  led  to  act  rationally. 

The  moral  agent  only  appears  to  us  at  his  best 
when  under  the  dominion  of  its  characteristic 
tendencies.  These  are,  therefore,  the  tendencies 
which  we  must  study,  co-ordinate,  and  arrange  in 
a  hierarchy,  in  order  to  make  a  synthetic  unity  of 
the  moral  ego. 

III. 
THE  MORAL  TENDENCIES. 

49.  Different  Tendencies,  Different  Doctrines. 

As  we  have  already  seen,  the  problem  wrhich  we  have 
to  solve  is  this : — What  is  the  tendency  or  system  of 
tendencies  which  is  the  best  fitted  to  characterise  a 
reasonable  being,  determined  to  action  by  a  moral 
will  ?  There  are  scarcely  any  tendencies  which  have 
not  in  turn  been  adopted  by  moralists  as  capable  of 
giving  rise  to  good  conduct ;  the  grossest  and  the 
most  refined  pleasures,  those  of  the  senses  as  wrell 
as  of  the  aesthetic  taste  and  of  the  "  intellect,"  have 
been  recommended  to  virtuous  man ;  the  egoistic 
tendencies  as  well  as  the  altruistic,  the  tendency  to 
inaction  as  well  as  the  tendency  to  effort,  have  been 
equally  extolled.  In  general,  an  incomplete  view  of 
the  exigencies  of  human  nature,  and  ignorance  or 
contempt  for  some  of  the  normal  tendencies  of  man, 
have  been  the  cause  of  the  adoption  of  moral  theories 
which  are  unsatisfactory  when  we  consider  their 
remoteness  from  psycho-sociological  reality. 


NATURALISM.  95 

50.  Naturalism. 

Because  to  live  according  to  nature  seems  normal 
to  most  men,  some  writers,  for  instance,  after  an 
imperfect  enumeration  of  the  various  forms  of  life 
according  to  nature,  impose  on  man  as  directing 
tendencies  of  conduct  the  same  tendencies  which 
determine  the  course  of  animal  existence. 

Epicurus  and  Spencer  agree  in  asserting  that  the 
search  for  pleasure  being  common  to  all  natural 
beings,  this  search  must  be  the  motive  of  human 
actions.1  Admitting  that  the  desire  of  enjoyment  is 
the  predominant  desire  in  most  men,  it  would  not 
necessarily  follow  that  it  remains  the  predominant 
desire  of  all  reasonable  beings,  and  a  fortiori,  if  it  is 
merely  ascertained  that  it  is  a  general  appetition  in 
the  animal  series.  No  doubt  we  cannot  form  a  great 
gulf  between  the  human  and  other  living  species ;  we 
can  believe  in  the  continuity  of  universal  evolution, 
and  in  particular  of  animal  evolution,  and  we  ought 
to  admit  it  more  and  more  as  a  scientific  fact.  We 
therefore  are  free  from  the  prejudice  which  makes 
certain  moralists  say  that  it  is  exactly  because  such 
and  such  a  mode  of  action  is  animal,  that  man  ought 
to  regard  it  as  unworthy  of  him,  and  rather  adopt 
the  contrary  mode  of  action ;  such  a  prejudice  is 
too  obviously  the  mark  of  the  metaphysical  mind 
which  imagines  the  distinction  and  opposition 
between  matter,  "flesh,"  and  "spirit." 

1  Vide  Spencer,  77/6'  Data  of  Ethics,  chap.  iii.  p.  46  (1879): 
"  Pleasure  somewhere,  at  some  time,  to  some  being  or  beings,  is  an 
inexpugnable  element  of  the  conception.  It  is  as  much  a  necessary 
form  of  moral  intuition  as  space  is  a  necessary  form  of  intellectual 
intuition." — TR. 


96  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

But,  to  refuse  to  see  in  man  any  new  tendency 
superior  to  those  experienced  by  animals,  is  also 
the  denial  of  a  scientific  fact — viz.,  the  progressive 
perfection  of  the  animal  species.  The  same 
difficulty  which  makes  it  so  hard  for  psychologists 
to  agree  on  the  nature  of  rational  mental  activity, 
easily  leads  moralists  to  exaggerate  two  contrary 
tendencies,  the  tendency  to  assimilate  completely 
human  to  animal  conduct,  and  the  tendency  to 
draw  a  profound  distinction  between  them.  So  that 
the  general  solution,  which,  without  disposing  of 
the  particular  questions,  makes  them  more  easily 
approached,  should  be  the  same. 

Human  reason  does  not  differ  fundamentally  from 
animal  intelligence;  it  is  only  a  perfected  form  of 
it.  While  the  animal  associates  images,  man  in 
his  judgments  takes  consciousness  of  his  power 
of  association,  and  affirms  the  objective  value 
(attributed  spontaneously  by  the  animal  to  its 
representative  synthesis,  itself  spontaneous)  of  the 
reflective  synthesis  he  effects.  While  the  animal 
is  content  with  practical  inferences  which  make  him 
avoid  a  stick  like  that  with  which  he  has  been  beaten 
and  a  fire  like  the  fire  which  has  burned  him,  man, 
by  reflection  on  his  mental  operations,  analyses  them, 
distinguishes  between  their  different  stages  in  order 
to  place  them  side  by  side  after  having  separated 
them  and  reasoned  on  them.  While  the  animal  is 
capable  of  classing  objects  from  the  point  of  view  of 
their  utility  or  its  own  particular  likings,  man  classes 
them  according  to  the  most  general  and  most  dis- 
interested tendencies  from  the  universal  point  of 
view.  He  thus  reaches  the  idea  of  necessity  and 
law,  and  then,  thanks  to  science,  he  moves  by  rapid 


NATURALISM.  Q7 

steps  from  the  lower  stage,  which  was  his  point 
of  departure,  and  which  remains  the  last  term  of 
the  mental  evolution  of  animals.1  It  is,  therefore, 
reflection,  the  higher  degree  of  attention  paid 
by  a  being  to  himself,  which  constitutes,  from 
the  speculative  point  of  view,  the  superiority  of 
man.  This  superiority  involves  a  greater  elevation 
of  sentiment,  the  appearance  of  aesthetic,  religious, 
intellectual,  and  social  tendencies,  of  which  only  the 
veriest  rudiments  are  to  be  seen  in  the  mind  of  beasts. 
But  just  as  the  human  use  of  reason  is  a  con- 
tinuation of  animal  intelligence,  and  constitutes  an 
efflorescence  of  nature  from  the  intellectual  point 
of  view,  so  the  disinterested,  aesthetic,  religious 
sentiments,  etc.,  which  are  the  glory  of  humanity, 
are  not  external  to  nature,  are  not  in  opposition  to 
the  appetites  and  tendencies  of  animals,  but  rather 
constitute  their  legitimate  end. 

Pleasure  results  from  the  gratification  of  a  tend- 
ency, on  condition  that  the  lack  of  gratification 
of  other  tendencies  does  not  involve  keener  dis- 
comfort. The  animal  experiences  pleasure  in  satisfy- 
ing his  instinctive  activity  without  a  check;  as  we 
have  seen,  it  has  an  appetite,  or  a  small  number  of 
predominant  appetites,  wrhich  constitute  the  ordinary 
source  of  its  pleasures  and  pains.  In  man  this  is  far 
from  being  the  case ;  instinctive  activity  is  almost 
evanescent ;  the  instinct  of  preservation  and  the 
sexual  instinct  have  lost  most  of  their  blind  and 
automatic  although  well-defined  characters  of 
activity;  and  the  most  diverse  tendencies  may 
acquire  preponderance  according  to  the  individual, 

1  Cf.  Romanes,  Mental  Evolution  in  Animals  and  Mental  Evolution 
in  Man. 

7 


gS  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

the  temperament,  and  the  environment.  Thus  we 
see  in  certain  men  the  most  delicate  sensibility 
destroyed,  or  at  any  rate  lessened,  by  the  grossest 
pleasures,  and  even  this  refined  sensibility  becomes 
the  lot  of  the  few.  Some  find  their  greatest  pleasure 
in  the  exercise  of  power,  in  the  wielding  of  authority, 
and  others  in  a  state  of  tranquillity  which  is  not 
untainted  by  servility;  others  in  self-renunciation, 
charity,  love;  and  others,  again,  in  perpetual  amuse- 
ment. When  it  is  claimed  that  a  man  ought  to  seek 
his  pleasures  like  the  animal,  we  forget  the  differ- 
ence that  a  higher  degree  of  evolution  has  effected 
between  the  two  modes  of  activity — animal  pursuit 
and  human  conduct. 

51.  Hedonism.1 

The  precept,  "  Seek  your  pleasures,"  may  be 
used  in  a  twofold  sense.  The  first,  "  Seek  each 
the  pleasure  that  gives  you  the  activity  most 
in  conformity  with  your  predominant  tendency," 
furnishes  us  with  a  precept  of  moral  anomia,  of 
social  anarchy,  and  brings  us  directly  to  a  type  of 
conduct  very  different  to  that  of  the  brute;  for  the 
brute  at  least  subordinates  his  different  interests  to 
the  vital  interest  safeguarded  by  his  instinct;  while 
the  man  who  does  not  conceive  a  hierarchy  of- 
pleasures,  a  scale  of  values,  and  a  scale  of  interests, 
is  capable  of  subordinating  his  vital  interests  to 
harmful  pleasures. 

1  On  this  section  the  following  may  be  read  with  advantage  : — 
Lecky,  History  of  European  Morals  (1890),  vol.  i.  chap.  i.  ;  Bain, 
Mental  and  Moral  Science,  Book  IV. ,  chap.  iv. ;  The  Emotions  and 
the  Will,  chap,  viii.,  "The  Will";  Mackenzie,  Manual  of  Ethics, 
chap,  vi.;  Sorley,  Ethics  of  Naturalism,  chap.  vii. 


HEDONISM.  99 

But  if  we  give  to  the  precept  the  second  mean- 
ing that  it  may  have,  "  Seek  the  pleasure  that 
is  most  in  conformity  with  human  nature," 
from  that  moment  we  formulate  a  command 
which  requires  numerous  commentaries,  which  can 
only  be  carried  out  at  the  cost  of  considerable 
reflection,  which  implies  lofty  ideas,  and  in  the 
front  rank  of  those  ideas,  the  idea  of  duty.  For 
to  command  a  man  to  seek  that  mode  of  activity 
which  pleases  him  best,  is  scarcely  to  command,  in 
the  proper  sense  of  the  word.  At  most  it  is  to 
approve  of  his  giving  himself  up  to  moral  anarchy, 
to  encourage  him  to  persevere  in  a  method  of  con- 
duct which  it  is  far  too  easy  for  him  to  adopt.  But 
to  command  him  to  seek  the  pleasure  which  is  most 
in  conformity  with  human  nature,  is  to  oppose  to  the 
choice  to  which  his  individual  character  would  have 
led  him,  the  choice  that  every  reasonable  being  ought 
to  make  in  order  to  experience  a  pleasure  which  every 
man  should  endeavour  to  experience  in  order  to  be 
a  man  in  the  fullest  sense  of  the  word. 

And  what  in  the  opinion  of  the  various  moralists 
is  this  pleasure  ?  Have  they  thoroughly  analysed 
human  nature  ?  have  they  not  neglected  one  of  the 
important  indications  of  psychology  and  sociology 
by  calling  pleasure  supreme  ?  That  is  the  question 
wrhich  wre  must  now  ask  ourselves.  It  is  true  that  we 
cannot  a  priori  refuse  to  pleasure  a  place  in  ethics. 
Pleasure  is  one  of  the  most  important  psychical 
phenomena;  and  a  morality  which  does  not  take 
pleasure  into  account  is  purely  theoretical  and  use- 
less; as  we  have  seen,  concrete  beings  are  not  moved 
by  abstract  ideas,  but  by  the  arousing  of  tendencies, 
and  every  tendency  issues  in  either  pleasure  or 


100  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

pain.  Now  pain  determines  movements  of  repulsion 
or  aversion ;  pleasure  determines  movements  of 
attraction,  appetitions  which  keep  alive  the  primi- 
tive tendency  and  develop  it  instead  of  destroying 
it.  For  a  precept  to  act  on  man,  not  only  must  it 
correspond  to  a  tendency,  but  this  tendency  must 
also  be  strong  enough  to  procure  pleasure,  a  pleasure 
as  far  as  possible  without  pain,  which  demands  no 
too  painful  a  sacrifice,  or  which  procures  an  intense 
pleasure  by  virtue  of  the  sacrifice.1 

But  the  tendency  to  experience  pleasure  and  to 
avoid  pain  is  not  the  first  of  all,  either  in  the  psycho- 
genetic  order,  or  in  the  order  of  relative  importance. 
In  fact  the  tendency  manifested  by  the  new-born 
child,  which  is  met  hardly  anywhere  else  but  in  the 
lower  stages  of  idiocy,2  and  which  subsists  to  the  last 
in  the  insane,  is  the  tendency  to  eat  whatever  comes 
within  reach  (even  things  that  are  disgusting,  as 
do  idiots  and  certain  classes  of  the  insane,  without 
appearing  to  experience  either  pleasure  or  pain, 
except  perhaps  at  the  moment  when  the  stomach 
is  replete).3  This  instinct  is  the  first  specific  phase 
of  the  instinct  of  preservation,  an  instinct  which 
later  arouses  tendencies  of  appetition  or  repulsion 
when  agreeable  and  painful  emotions  are  sufficiently 
differentiated  and  have  become  the  signs  either  of  the 
useful  or  the  good,  or  of  the  harmful  or  the  bad. 

Besides,  the  tendency  to  seek  pleasure  enters  into 
conflict  at  a  later  stage  with  the  instinct  of  preserva- 

1  Cf.  J.  S.  Mill,  Utilitarianism  (1891),  p.  23.— TR. 

2  We  do  not  say  in  the  "lowest"  stage,  because  certain  idiots  have 
not  even  the  instinct  of  preservation  under  the  form  of  the  instinct  of 
nutrition. 

3  Cf.  Mercier,  Sanity  and  Insanity,   pp.   287  et  seq.\    Ribot,    The 
Psychology  of  the  Emotions,  pp.  200  et  seq,  —  TR. 


EPICUREANISM.  IOI 

tion  with  which  at  first  it  is  intimately  allied.  This 
is  because  the  agreeable  emotions  are  associated  with 
numerous  modes  of  activity,  more  or  less  remote 
from  the  modes  adapted  simply  to  the  preservation 
of  existence,  and  because  from  the  tendency  to  pre- 
servation inevitably  springs  the  tendency  to  develop- 
ment, which  gives  rise  to  innovations,  some  useful 
and  some  harmful ;  and  it  is  found  that  certain  harm- 
ful innovations  have,  nevertheless,  been  agreeable, 
because  pleasure  is  not  a  sign  invented  by  nature 'to 
warn  man  of  what  constitutes  his  good;  because 
pleasure  is  the  psychical  result  of  biological  modi- 
fications, multiple  reflexes,  and  other  organic  phe- 
nomena that  may  be  determined  by  a  poison  as 
well  as  by  a  healthy  beverage,  and  by  morbid  as 
well  as  by  moral  activity. 


52.  Epicureanism.1 

Epicurus  seems  to  have  understood  this,  for  he 
has  divided  desires  into  three  classes — (i)  Natural 
and  necessary  desires;  (2)  desires  which  are  only 
natural;  and  (3)  desires  neither  natural  nor  neces- 
sary— and  only  conceded  the  satisfaction  of  natural 
and  necessary  desires,  and  therefore  of  those  which 
are  the  strongest  and  most  capable  of  procuring 
pleasure  without  too  keen  an  accompanying  dis- 
comfort. But  is  his  enumeration  of  the  natural 
and  necessary  desires  complete  ? 

It  has  been  said  that  the  morality  of  this  philo- 
sopher issues  in  the  morality  of  "dry  bread."  It 
is,  in  fact,  essentially  negative.  Every  pleasure 

1  Diog.  Laert.,  x.  149.     Cf.  Guyau,  La  Morale  d'Epictire,  chap.  iv. , 
pp.  45-57.— TR. 


102  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

resulting  from  action  must  be  avoided  as  uncertain, 
unstable,  and  likely  to  produce  in  the  future  more 
pain  than  pleasure.  The  wise  man  must,  therefore, 
content  himself  with  the  restful  pleasure  which  con- 
sists in  a  natural  tendency  to  satisfy  his  most  press- 
ing needs,  those  of  food:  "He  who  lives  on  dry 
bread  and  water  need  envy  Jupiter  in  nothing." l 
Throughout  the  doctrine  of  Epicurus  there  are 
certain  signs  of  a  positive  conception  of  human 
happiness.  First,  there  is  the  distinction  between 
corporeal  pleasures,  which  are  momentary,  and  the 
pleasures  of  the  mind,  which  are  accumulative,  and 
perpetuated  by  foresight  and  memory.2  No  doubt 
the  pleasure  of  the  soul  consists  in  prevision  and 
recollection  of  the  apathy  induced  by  the  gratifica- 
tion of  the  natural  and  necessary  desires  of  the  body; 
but  it  would  be  remarkable  if  a  Greek,  seeing  to  how 
large  a  degree  his  tendencies  were  speculative,  had 
not  conceived  beyond  the  corporeal  apathy  a  mental 
ataraxia3  permitting  some  of  the  pleasures  of  the 
intellect.  We  find  an  explicit  trace  of  this  concep- 
tion in  the  Epicurean  theology,  in  which  we  see  the 
gods  who  are  only  superior  men  placed  in  the  "  inter- 
worlds"  there  to  live  happily,  needing  neither  sleep 
nor  food,  because  they  taste  the  charms  of  conversation 
and  of  the  loftiest  intellectual  life.  For  they  are  beau- 
tiful and  reasonable;  they  enjoy  that  intellect  which, 
as  Epicurus  himself  asserts,  is  the  greatest  good.4 

Whatever  view  we  may  take   on   this  particular 
point,   there  is   no  doubt  that  the  Epicurean  con- 

1  Cf.  Diog.  Laert.,  xi.  pp.  130-46. 

2  Op.  «'/.,  p.  137. 

3  Ribot,  The  Psychology  of  the  Emotions,  p.  360. — TR. 

4  Op.  cit.,  p.  131. 


UTILITARIANISM.  IO3 

ception  of  supreme  pleasure  is  incomplete,  and  in- 
adequate to  the  requirements  of  human  nature. 
Even  admitting  that  Epicurus  has  prescribed  the 
search  for  pleasure  which  results  in  the  free  exercise 
of  the  intellect,  we  must  not  forget  that  he  has 
formally  banished  the  pleasures  of  social  and  family 
life,  and  ipso  facto  all  the  gratification  which  may 
result  from  disinterested  intercourse  with  other  men, 
with  art,  and  with  politics.  He  has  impaired  human 
existence,  deprived  it  of  most  of  its  attractions,  and 
has  reduced  to  a  minimum  its  requirements.  Instead 
of  trying  to  subordinate  the  different  desires  to  one 
another,  he  has  suppressed  nearly  all  of  them,  only 
retaining  that  without  which  the  most  restricted 
human  life  would  be  almost  inconceivable — the  desire 
of  satisfying  hunger.  He  has  not  even  endeavoured 
to  give  to  the  sexual  instinct,  powerful  as  it  is,  and 
prompt  as  it  is  in  its  vengeance  on  those  who  abuse 
it,  the  satisfaction  that  is  its  due. 

To  sum  up,  the  morality  of  Epicurus  is  the 
apotheosis  of  idleness,  of  that  moral  inertia  which 
tends  to  realise  an  unnatural  physical  inertia.  To 
criticise  it  from  the  psychological  point  of  view,  it 
appears  to  be  the  result  of  a  huge  blunder,  or  at 
least  of  a  pathological  conception  of  human  nature. 
Asceticism  alone  has  gone  further  in  this  direction 
than  Epicureanism. 


53.   Utilitarianism. 

The  practical  mind  of  the  English  philosophers 
has  led  them  to  reject  the  ascetic3  and  to  retain  the 
utilitarian  principle  of  Epicurus.  They  did  not  wish 

3  Bentham,  Theory  of  Legislation,  chap,  ii.— TR. 


104  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

to  deprive  themselves  of  the  varied  pleasures  of 
human  life,  but  they  endeavoured  to  choose  the 
pleasures  which  would  bring  to  them  after  a  longer 
or  shorter  interval  happiness  of  the  most  lasting  and 
most  durable  character. 

This  was  the  reason  of  the  "arithmetic  of 
pleasure,"  heralded  by  Bentham,1  careful,  like  his 
compatriot  Priestley,  of  "the  greatest  happiness  of 
the  greatest  number."  Although  they  dwelt  but 
little  on  human  solidarity,  the  fact  of  a  profound 
community  of  'interests  was  none  the  less  accepted 
at  the  end  of  the  eighteenth  century,  and  even  at 
that  time  there  was  no  endeavour  to  separate  indi- 
vidual from  collective  well-being.  Besides,  sympathy 
appeared,  if  not  to  all  as  a  factor  of  morality,  at  least 
in  general  as  a  natural  phenomenon  which  must  be 
taken  into  account;  brutal  egoism  seemed  clumsy 
even  to  individuals  who  saw  in  the  sacrifice  of 
certain  petty  private  satisfactions  to  the  common 
benefit  a  skilful  operation  destined  to  procure  for 
the  agent  many  more  advantages  than  those  he 
sacrifices. 

Morality  therefore  became  an  affair  of  calculation 
and  intelligent  choice  of  the  acts  most  suited  to 
safeguard  private  and  collective  interests,  as  inti- 
mately connected  as  possible.  What  reproach  could 
be  laid  to  the  charge  of  a  morality  which  took  into 
account  all  human  interests,  from  economic  interests 
to  aesthetic,  and  which  endeavoured  to  induce  men 
to  adopt  every  mode  of  activity  which  would  lead  to 
the  most  complete  satisfaction  of  our  tendencies 
both  as  individuals  and  as  social  beings  ?  Could 

1  "On  Bentham  and  Epicurus,"  vide  Guyau,  La  Morale  Anglaise 
Contemporaine^  chap,  i.,  p.  13. — TR. 


INTEREST   AND    DESIRE.  IO5 

it  be  reproached  with  not  proving  the  necessity  of 
the  conduct  it  commended  ?  It  would  answer  tri- 
umphantly, though  indirectly,  by  pointing  to  the 
number  of  attractions  which  it  presented  to  the 
sensible  being,  the  power  that  is  conferred  upon  it 
by  the  promises  of  happiness  that  it  could  make 
and  fulfil;  by  affirming  that  there  is  no  moral  law 
in  the  sense  of  the  word  law  in  general — that  is  to 
say,  so  far  as  its  necessary  and  inevitable  relation 
is  concerned;  that  there  are  moral  precepts  the 
value,  and  a  fortiori  the  necessity,  of  which  can 
always  be  contested;  but  that  in  the  hierarchy  of 
moral  precepts  the  highest  place  is  occupied  by  the 
most  efficacious.  And  not  one  of  them  would  be 
more  efficacious  than  that  which  would  correspond 
to  every  human  tendency,  which  would  clash  with 
none,  and  which  could,  if  followed  up,  give  com- 
plete happiness  or  at  least  the  greatest  happiness 
possible. 

We  cannot,  therefore,  discredit  a  moral  theory 
which  would  satisfy  all  interests  and  prescribe  what 
is  useful  to  them  as  a  full  safeguard.  But  it  should 
be  preceded  by  another  theory,  having  as  its  object 
the  reduction  of  the  diversity  of  human  interests  to 
the  unity  of  a  system,  for  we  know  by  experience 
that  they  can  never  be  reconciled  as  long  as  they 
are  in  isolation. 


54.  Interest  and  Desire. 

If  you  separate  interest  from  desire,  you  may  no 
doubt  assert  that  my  interest,  properly  understood, 
is  identical  with  yours.  But  from  my  point  of  view 
your  claim  cannot  be  allowed,  for  my  interest  is 


IO6  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

what  is  good  for  me,  and  that  alone  appears  to  me 
good  which  is  in  conformity  with  my  desire.  Modify 
my  desires,  change  my  tendencies,  and  prove  to  me 
that  they  are  bad.  If  you  succeed  in  convincing  me, 
and  if  we  go  so  far  as  to  have  the  same  or  recon- 
cilable desires,  we  shall  have  the  same  interests,  or 
interests  which  are  either  complementary  or  in 
harmony.  But  to  modify  my  tendencies  being  pre- 
cisely the  immediate  object  of  morality,  you  will 
be  arguing  in  a  vicious  circle  if  you  claim  to  base 
your  moral  theory  on  the  postulate  of  the  funda- 
mental harmony  of  interests,  or  of  their  natural 
subordination. 

So  far  as  the  reasonable  will,  in  harmony  with 
science,  does  not  intervene  to  establish  in  the  most 
objective  possible  manner  a  scale  of  values,  a  hier- 
archy of  ends,  such  that  an  end  becomes  a  mean 
for  a  higher  end,  useful  in  its  turn  for  the  realisation 
of  a  still  higher  end;  so  far  as  one  is  not  brought 
in  consequence  to  the  highest  psychological  and 
sociological  considerations,  the  utilitarian  formulae 
remain  with  no  wider  scope  than  that  of  a  general 
precept  which  meets  with  too  little  opposition  to 
remain  the  sole  precept  of  morality.  "Do  what 
is  useful  for  the  realisation  of  the  good"  is  to  say 
"He  who  wants  the  ends  wants  the  means,"  and 
that  is  saying  nothing  at  all. 


55.  Egoism. 

In  fact,  the  utilitarian  doctrine  only  takes  a  par- 
ticular aspect  when  it  is  opposed  to  the  morality  of 
disinterestedness,  of  generosity,  and  of  the  love  of 


EGOISM.  107 

others,  and  becomes  clearly  the  morality  of  an  indi- 
vidual or  collective  egoism.1 

The  utilitarian,  in  the  true  sense  of  the  word,  does 
nothing  from  aesthetic  or  intellectual  interest,  nothing 
from  devotion  to  an  ideal  out  of  which  he  does  not 
know  whether  or  not  he  can  extract  some  advantage 
or  pleasure.  The  type  of  the  utilitarian  is  the  busi- 
ness man,  the  Englishman  on  whose  lips  is  always 
the  famous  word  "business,"  and  who  in  matters 
of  love,  or  religion,  or  aesthetics,  never  forgets  his 
business. 

It  is  not  long  before  such  a  man  is  inconsequent  with 
himself,  just  as  the  miser  who  from  the  preliminary 
search  for  gold  as  a  means  of  procuring  for  himself 
pleasure  or  happiness,  is  not  long  before  he  takes  the 
means  for  the  end,  and  the  possession  of  gold  as  the 
principal  object  of  his  activity.  John  Stuart  Mill 
has  admirably  shown  how,  as  an  effect  of  the  associa- 
tion of  ideas,  the  means  so  closely  associate  them- 
selves with  the  end  that  they  become  the  unique 
term  close  behind  which  the  term  that  is  passed 
disappears  in  the  distance.2  (In  this  way  also  is 
explained  man's  search  for  virtue  and  moral  value.) 

The  horizon  of  the  utilitarian  then  becomes  more 

1  "  I  think,"  says  M.  Renouvier  (Science  de  la  Morale,  vol.  i.  p.  194), 
"  that  there  is  no  abuse  of  ordinary  language  in  using  the  word  interest 
to  indicate  the  group  of  human  ends  which  comprises  three  forms  of 
good  or  elements  of  happiness:  (i)  those  which  directly  concern  the 
observation  of  the  individual ;  (2)  those  which  concern  his  powers  of 
the  material  or  impulsive  order  when  his  passions  have  only  himself 
as  their  end  ;  (3)  his  means  or  his  accumulative  power  of  preserva- 
tion and  enjoyment.  .  .  .  Utility  like  interest  has  a  collective  direction, 
but  does  not  cease  to  be  applied  to  the  individual  and  his  material 
good  in  the  final  analysis." 

3  Mill's  Utilitarianism,  1891,  pp.  54  et  seq.\  Sorley,  Ethics  of 
Naturalism,  pp.  134  ct  seq. — TR. 


108  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

and  more  restricted.  First  of  all  desirous  to  procure 
for  himself  the  means  that  are  useful  to  the  loftiest 
satisfactions,  whether  of  an  intellectual,  aesthetic, 
or  social  order,  he  little  by  little  comes  to  search 
for  the  means  that  are  useful  to  the  satisfaction  of 
appetites  which  are  common  to  man  and  to  the 
animal. 

In  vain  was  John  Stuart  Mill's  famous  declara- 
tion:1 "I  would  rather  be  a  discontented  Socrates 
than  a  satisfied  pig;"  most  of  his  disciples  were  not 
long  before  they  considered  Socrates  as  a  dreamer,  a 
Utopian,  a  man  who  did  not  know  how  to  conduct 
his  business,  and  preferred  to  that  unfortunate  sage 
the  happy  merchant  who,  without  any  elevation  of 
mind  or  heart,  succeeds  in  his  enterprises,  enriches 
himself,  and  assures  for  himself  an  existence  of 
gaiety  and  good  living. 

Such  utilitarians  give  us  an  excellent  instance  of 
the  theoretical  insufficiency  of  utilitarianism ;  they 
show  the  practical  powerlessness  of  a  doctrine, 
definitively  directed,  but  incapable  of  being  rigor- 
ously systematic.  The  formula,  "  the  greatest 
happiness  of  the  greatest  number,"  will  be  an 
empty  formula  as  long  as  the  happiness  that  is 
sought  for  is  not  better  defined.  The  worst  of 
tyrants  will  pretend  that  he  is  causing  the  happiness 
of  the  greatest  number  of  his  subjects  by  putting  to 
death,  exiling,  or  imprisoning  all  those  who  do  not 
think  as  he  does.  The  most  anarchist  of  theorists 
may  on  his  side  claim  to  make  people  happy  by 
allowing  each  to  act  according  to  his  own  sweet  will. 

1  "  It  is  better  to  be  a  human  being  dissatisfied  than  a  pig  satisfied  ; 
better  to  be  Socrates  dissatisfied  than  a  fool  satisfied."  Utilitarianism , 
p.  M.-TR. 


THE    COLLECTIVE    INTEREST.  IOQ 

56.  The  Collective  Interest. 

The  sacrifice  of  individual  to  collective  interest 
can  only  be  prescribed  when  the  collective  interest 
is  well  defined.  Now,  collective  interest  is  either,  as 
some  of  the  best  thinkers  conceive  it,  in  conflict  with 
the  opinions  of  the  masses,  or  in  conformity  with  the 
aspirations  of  the  greatest  number.  In  the  first  case 
we  may  be  well  assured  that  the  masses  will  be 
ignorant  of  those  interests  that  some  assert  are 
veritably  theirs,  and  these  worthy  souls  will  sacrifice 
themselves  to  no  purpose  without  finding  any  other 
satisfaction  than  that  of  duty  accomplished — viz.,  the 
satisfaction  of  the  conscience.  In  the  second  case 
they  will  give  way  to  the  impulse  of  the  masses  and 
the  pressure  of  the  mob,  rather  than  act  morally. 
They  will  resign  themselves  "to  a  large  number  of 
practices  which  will  not  be  less  obligatory  than 
others,  without,  however,  its  being  possible  to  see 
what  services  they  are  rendering  to  the  com- 
munity."1 

"  For  collective  utility  to  be  the  principle  of  moral 
action,  it  must  be  in  most  cases  the  object  of  a  fairly 
clear  representation  before  it  can  determine  the  con- 
duct. Now  utilitarian  calculations,  even  if  exact,  are 
combinations  of  ideas  which  are  too  subtle  to  act 
much  on  the  will,  .  .  .  since  the  interest  is  not 
immediate  and  perceptible,  it  is  too  feebly  conceived 
to  give  an  impulse  to  activity."2 

"  And  further,  nothing  is  so  obscure  as  these 
questions  of  utility.  However  slight  may  be  the 

1  Durkheim,  Division  du  Travail  social,  p.  12. 

2  We  must  not  forget,  in  fact,  that  interest  from  the  psychological 
point  of  view  is  inseparable  from  tendency,  and  that  the  keenest  tend- 
ency accompanies  the  clearest  and  most  concrete  representations. 


IIO  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

complexity  of  the  situation,  the  individual  no  longer 
sees  clearly  where  his  own  interest  lies.  .  .  .  But 
the  evidence  is  still  more  difficult  to  obtain  when  it 
is  the  interest,  not  of  an  individual,  but  of  a  society, 
which  is  at  stake.  .  .  .  And  even  if  we  were  to 
examine  the  rules,  the  social  utility  of  which  is 
most  amply  demonstrated,  we  see  that  the  services 
which  they  render  cannot  be  known  in  advance."1 

So  that  not  only  have  the  commandments  of 
morality  never,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  had  "as  their 
end  the  interest  of  society,"  but  it  is  impossible  to 
effectively  command  a  man  to  take  as  his  end 
the  safeguard  of  real  collective  interests,  when  he 
is  incapable  of  safeguarding  and  of  recognising  his 
real  personal  interests.  And  if  instead  of  real 
interests  we  simply  speak  of  the  ends  in  which 
an  individual  is  interested  because  of  his  tendencies, 
there  is  no  doubt  that  a  being  without  moral  culture, 
and  without  a  preliminary  idea  of  duty,  will 
spontaneously  interest  himself  more  in  what  corre- 
sponds to  his  strongest  tendencies — i.e.,  his  nearest 
and  most  personal  ends.  Remote  and  imperfect 
ends,  such  as  the  well-being  of  society  in  a  thousand 
years'  time,  will  leave  him  indifferent. 

It  is  true  that  it  is  objected  that,  as  a  matter  of 
fact,  there  is  no  conflict  possible  between  the  search 
for  real  individual  happiness  and  that  of  the  happi- 
ness of  the  greatest  number;  so  that  it  is  not  at  all 
necessary  for  the  individual  to  deliberately  propose 
to  himself  collective  happiness  as  his  end.  "  But  to 
speak  only  of  actions  done  from  the  motive  of  duty, 
and  in  direct  obedience  to  principle:  it  is,"  says  J.  S. 
Mill,2  "  a  misapprehension  of  the  utilitarian  mode  of 

J  Durkheim,  ibid.,  p.  14.  2  Utilitarianism,  p.  26. — TR. 


THE    COLLECTIVE    INTEREST.  Ill 

thought,  to  conceive  it  as  implying  that  people 
should  fix  their  minds  upon  so  wide  a  generality  as 
the  world,  or  society  at  large;  .  .  .  the  thoughts  of 
the  most  virtuous  man  need  not  on  these  occasions 
travel  beyond  the  particular  persons  concerned, 
except  so  far  as  is  necessary  to  assure  himself  that 
in  benefiting  them  he  is  not  violating  the  rights — 
that  is,  the  legitimate  and  authorised  expectations — 
of  any  one  else.  ...  The  occasions  on  which  any 
person  (except  one  in  a  thousand)  has  it  in  his  power 
to  do  this  on  an  extended  scale,  in  other  words  to  be 
a  public  benefactor,  are  but  exceptional :  and  on 
these  occasions  alone  is  he  called  on  to  consider 
public  utility." 

So  that  in  all  other  cases,  that  is  to  say  in  almost 
every  case,  the  utilitarian  will  think,  like  the  wise 
Epicurean,  of  himself,  or  at  most  of  a  small  circle  of 
friends.  Provided  that  he  abstains  "from  whatever 
is  manifestly  pernicious  to  society,"  by  being  useful 
to  himself  he  will  be  working  for  the  common  good. 
But,  then,  if  his  happiness  consists  in  this  gratifica- 
tion of  the  commonest  and  simplest  tendencies,  and 
if  only  the  most  foolish  things  are  of  interest  to  him, 
and  if  his  type  is  generalised  in  society,  shall  we  not 
reach  a  mode  of  social  existence  from  which  will  be 
banished,  not  only  every  lofty  and  generous  feeling, 
but  even  every  cordial  understanding  ?  For  nothing 
divides  men  more  than  low,  common,  and  inevitably 
selfish  sentiments. 

Can  one  prove  this  harmony  of  common  and  indi- 
vidual utility  otherwise  than  by  postulating  in  the 
individual  great  loftiness  of  thought  and  relatively  dis- 
interested tendencies,  or,  at  least,  interests  which  are 
outside  the  sphere  of  common  individual  interests  ? 


112  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

John  Stuart  Mill  seems  to  count  too  much  on  a 
moral  sense  developed  and  refined  among  all  men. 
"  Those  who  are  equally  acquainted  with,  and 
equally  capable  of  appreciating  and  enjoying  both 
[kinds  of  life],  do  give  a  most  marked  preference  to 
the  manner  of  existence  which  employs  their  higher 
faculties.  Few  human  creatures  would  consent  to  be 
changed  into  any  of  the  lower  animals;  ...  no  per- 
son of  feeling  and  conscience  would  be  selfish  and 
base."1 

But  these  people  who  are  susceptible  of  healthy 
appreciation,  and  these  men  of  feeling,  are  rare. 
These  are  not  the  men  who  have  most  need  of 
precepts  of  morality;  the  elevation  of  their  senti- 
ments would  almost  suffice  to  make  them  truly 
virtuous.  It  is  the  majority  of  men  who  lack  such 
elevation,  who  are  always  requiring  to  be  directed, 
raised,  and  brought  to  the  conception  of  an  ideal  of 
happiness  higher  than  that  which  they  can  imagine 
by  themselves.  Their  spontaneous  search  for  the 
useful  is  therefore  of  no  moral  value ;  their  happiness 
is  not  a  moral  happiness. 

And  this  is  the  crowning  condemnation  of  utili- 
tarianism ;  the  system  is  only  good  for  conspicuously 
moral  beings.2 


57.  Intellectual  Happiness. 

The  primordial  interest,  personal  or  collective, 
seems  to  be  that  of  self-preservation.  But  the 
tendency  of  the  being  to  persevere  in  his  being, 
which  Spinoza  proclaimed  to  be  the  very  essence  of 

1  Op.  cit.,  p.  12.— TR.         -  Cf.  Mackenzie,  op.  dt.,  pp.  103,  104. 


INTELLECTUAL   HAPPINESS.  113 

all  reality,  can  only  issue  in  immobility  and  stupor. 
Combined  with  the  tendency  to  change,  it  gives  rise 
to  a  desire  of  regular  development  which  may  be 
confounded  in  many  cases  with  the  desire  for 
happiness. 

What  is  happiness  in  fact  but  the  persistence  of  a 
desirable  state,  the  prolongation  without  fatigue  of  a 
pleasure,  and  therefore  of  quite  a  particular  pleasure, 
since  pleasure  in  general  (according  to  all  psycho- 
logists, and  also  for  physiological  reasons  connected 
with  nervous  exhaustion  and  modifications  in  the 
composition  of  the  blood)  is  followed  by  pain,  and 
transformed  more  or  less  promptly  into  a  painful 
feeling?1  The  state  of  happiness  does  not  admit  of 
violent  emotions  or  of  too  keen  an  excitement.  It 
is  much  less  compatible  with  the  sensorial  stimuli, 
with  mobility  of  mind  and  body,  than  with  the  in- 
tellectual and  contemplative  life,  or  with  moderate 
activity  and  the  peaceful  life.  And  that  is  why  the 
tendency  to  happiness  accommodates  itself  very  read- 
ily with  tendencies  to  the  intellectual  development 
and  to  the  exercise  of  the  rational  faculties. 

The  latter  tendencies,  as  we  have  seen,  are  human, 
and  we  must  not  underrate  their  importance.  By 
the  side  of  the  need  of  action,  which  is  as  animal  as 
it  is  human,  and  which  is  derived  directly  from  the 
necessity  to  life  of  development,  is  the  need  of  think- 
ing, reasoning,  assigning  causes,  discovering  laws, 
understanding  and  explaining,  which  is  properly 
human,  and  which  raises  in  certain  men  a  devotion 
to  science,  a  love  of  truth,  and  the  intensive  culture 
of  every  means  adapted  to  give  a  satisfactory  know- 

1  For  Pleasure- Pain  v.  Stout,  Manual  of  Psychology,  pp.  276-283. 
— TR. 

8 


114  THE   MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

ledge  of  things  and  of  oneself.  But  it  must  not 
become  exclusive. 

To  my  mind,  Aristotle,  after  having  laid  down  the 
principles  of  an  entirely  theoretical  morality,  had  the 
great  merit  of  recognising  that  this  ethic  is  rather 
better  for  gods  than  it  is  for  men.  "  It  is  not  qua 
man  but  qua  something  divine  residing  in  him  '?1  that 
man  is  called  upon  to  live  the  properly  intellectual  life, 
and  to  enjoy  the  happiness  that  follows  the  contempla- 
tion of  the  intellectual.  "  That,  no  doubt,  is  beyond 
human  nature,"  for  man  is  a  composite  being,  and 
has  a  soul  composed  not  only  of  intellectual  functions 
but  also  of  functions  that  are  nutritive,  sensitive, 
appetitive,  and  motive. 

It  is  none  the  less  true  that  to  Aristotle  the  moral 
ideal  is  precisely  that  activity  of  the  divinity  which 
experiences  no  passion  and  no  desire,  which  has 
nothing  to  will,  having  nothing  to  desire,  which  knows 
nothing  of  the  world,  and  delights  itself  in  eternal 
self-contemplation.  To  propose  to  man  as  a  distant 
end,  no  doubt,  but  as  the  supreme  object  of  the 
desire  which  moves  the  whole  world  (the  search  for 
the  divine),  this  purely  intellectual  perfection,  is  to 
prepare  the  wise  man,  who  has  only  a  practical 
wisdom  and  "  ethical  virtue,"  to  have  no  interest  in 
terrestrial  action  and  to  live  for  pure  speculation 
alone. 

Aristotle  himself  added  to  the  acute  observation 
to  which  we  have  just  referred,  a  precept  that  the 
mystics  will  interpret  wrongly,  although  in  itself  it  is 
harmless.  "  One  must  not,  because  one  is  a  man, 
have,  as  certain  people  point  out,  a  taste  for  human 
things,  and  because  one  is  mortal  a  taste  for  mortal 

1  Nice m achaean  Ethics^  Book  X.,  chap.  vii.  p.  10. — TR<    • 


MYSTICISM.  115 

things,  but  so  far  as  it  is  possible  we  must  make 
ourselves  immortal  and  do  all  we  can  to  live  in 
accordance  with  the  noblest  part  of  our  being."1 
Now  to  Aristotle  to  make  oneself  immortal  does  not 
mean  to  assure  for  oneself  a  personal  immortality,  an 
immortality  of  which  the  Greek  philosopher  did  not 
seem  to  have  any  very  clear  conception.  To  him  it 
meant  to  succeed  in  living  the  intellectual  life  which 
is  the  divine  and  imperishable  life. 

58.  Mysticism. 

Plotinus  and  the  neo-platonists  saw  in  this  passage 
from  their  master  a  confirmation  of  the  stimuli 
of  Plato,  according  to  whom  the  soul,  imprisoned  in 
the  body,2  must  ever  unceasingly  tend  to  escape  and 
endeavour  to  break  the  bonds  by  which  it  is  connected 
with  it. 

The  mysticism  which  has  as  its  consequence 
morbid  ecstasy3  is  thus  the  issue  of  a  moral  theory 
which  tries  to  raise  men's  ideals  far  above  human 
miseries.  To  wish  to  enter  into  communion  with  a 
divinity  which  has  hardly  anything  human  about  it, 
which  we  conceive  as  bodiless  and  almost  soulless, 
since  it  is  nothing  but  a  pure  spirit,  is  not  merely  to 
attempt  the  impossible,  but  it  is  to  give  way  to 
madness. 

Mysticism  can  only  flourish  by  the  abandonment 
of  manly  thoughts,  by  the  renunciation  of  the  exercise 
of  his  reason  by  the  reasonable  being,  for  to  exercise 

1  Op.  cit.t  Book  X.,  chap.  vii.  p.  12. 

2  "Like  an  oyster  in   its   shell,"    Phaedrus^  250;    the  body  is  an 
enclosure  or  prison  in  which  the  soul  is  incarcerated,   Crat.  400. — TR. 

3  Cf.  Sidgwick,  History  of  Ethics,  pp.  105-108.— TR. 


Il6  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

his  reason  is  to  judge  with  his  will  when  he  only 
affirms  or  denies  according  to  human  tendencies. 
Now  human  tendencies,  unless  they  are  morbid,  are 
not  attracted  by  the  unknowable,  by  the  mysterious, 
incomprehensible  being,  the  very  conception  of  wrhich 
demands  an  effort  which  can  only  be  translated  in 
our  language  by  giving  it  its  full  meaning — ex- 
travagance. 

The  morality  of  the  mystic  is  that  of  morbid 
impulses,  hallucinatory  visions,  and  delirious  con- 
ceptions. Such  is  the  fatal  result  of  the  disequili- 
bration  of  the  mental  functions  when  it  is  a  question 
of  giving  absolute  predominance  either  to  pure  in- 
tellect or  to  pure  love. 

The  mysticism  of  the  present  day  has  sometimes 
taken  one  of  the  varied  forms  of  eroticism.1  Men 
seek  a  subtilised  form  of  love  which  has  nothing 
human  about  it,  and  in  which  there  is  no  "  fleshly 
passion."  They  only  succeed  in  realising  this  extra- 
ordinary sentiment  by  a  distortion  of  normal  love. 
The  latter  is  at  first  quite  inseparable  from  the  sexual 
instinct;  but  there  are  perversions  of  the  sexual 
instinct  which  only  allow  a  few  general  character- 
istics of  the  multiple  characters  of  the  corresponding 
impulse  to  subsist.  In  certain  cases  the  primitive 
love  of  the  individuals  of  a  sex  for  the  individuals  of 
another  sex  becomes  a  vague  love  of  humanity,  and 
in  other  cases,  an  equally  vague  love  of  a  divinity 
that  is  only  partially  conceived. 

To  this  is  due  the  morbid  aspect  of  the  religion  of 
humanity  in  certain  Positivists,  and  especially  in 
Auguste  Comte  during  the  latter  part  of  his  life. 

1  Havelock  Ellis,  Psychology  of  Sex,  ii.  pp.  267  et  seq. ;  Ribot, 
The  Psychology  of  the  Emotions  >  pp.  99,  319. — TR. 


THE    ETHICS   OF   SPINOZA.  117 

This  new  religion,  endeavouring  to  replace  the  moral 
practice  inspired  by  positive  precepts,  differs  but 
little  from  the  ethico-religious  practices  which  are 
based  on  the  love  of  God:  it  is  still  a  mysticism,  for 
it  claims  to  develop  in  man  a  sentiment  which  nor- 
mally can  have  no  place  in  his  heart;  the  love  of 
Humanity  in  general  differs  as  much  from  the  love 
of  concrete  beings  as  the  love  of  the  unknowable, 
which  men  always  conceive  under  some  particular 
aspect,  differs  from  it. 

We  cannot  ask  a  man  to  sacrifice  his  pleasures, 
and  the  delights  of  his  present  existence,  and  his 
tendencies,  which  are  usually  directed  towards  ends 
not  remote  or  to  present  objects,  to  the  sole  desire 
of  divine  happiness  or  the  happiness  of  a  vague 
Humanity  throughout  thousands  of  years ;  this 
desire,  aroused  by  confused  or  abstracted  notions, 
will  never  have  any  real  efficacy  save  on  morbid 
minds,  inflamed  against  nature,  trying  to  crush 
every  natural  instinct  and  every  really  human  in- 
clination, and  only  taking  delight  in  so  precarious 
an  amusement,  because  of  the  disequilibration  of 
their  condition. 


59.  The  Ethics  of  Spinoza. 

A  great  philosopher  has  proposed  to  man  a  love  of 
God,  of  reason,  and  of  humanity  as  a  whole,  which 
may  be  substituted  for  all  the  other  sentiments, 
which  may  destroy  them  all,  and  of  itself  assure 
happiness.  This,  I  think,  adequately  characterises 
Spinoza  and  his  celebrated  theory  of  the  "  amor 
Dei  intellectualis." 

His  whole  ethics  tends  to  show  that  human  passions 


Il8  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

are  due  to  confused  visions,  and  notably  to  ignor- 
ance of  the  true  cause  of  phenomena.  To  avoid  the 
slavery  of  the  passions,  and  to  become  at  the  same 
time  active  and  free,  every  event  must  be  referred  to 
God,  to  the  unique  substance  which  is  the  sole  cause 
of  it  through  the  inevitable  inter-relations  of  pheno- 
mena. To  see  the  necessity  of  what  is,  to  consider 
oneself  and  all  other  beings  as  a  necessary  mode  of  a 
divine  attribute,  to  win  immortality  for  one's  soul  by 
making  of  it  a  thought  exactly  corresponding  to  the 
"  idea  which  necessarily  expresses  the  essence  of  the 
human  body  in  God," 1  or  "  an  idea  w7hich  expresses  the 
essence  of  the  human  body  sub  specie  ceternitatis 2 — that 
should  be  the  principal  care  of  the  wise.  The  duty  of 
the  disciple  of  Spinoza,  as  well  as  of  the  follower  of 
Aristotle,  is  to  make  himself  immortal  by  avoiding  all 
natural  passions.  "  From  the  third  type  of  adequate 
knowledge  (intuitive  knowledge  of  things  seen  under 
the  aspect  of  eternity)  necessarily  arises  the  intel- 
lectual love  of  God.  For  from  this  kind  of  know- 
ledge results  the  joy  accompanying  the  conception 
of  God  as  cause,  which,  by  the  fifth  definition  of  the 
passions,  constitutes  the  love  of  God,  in  so  far  as  we 
conceive  it  eternal,  and  that  is  wrhat  I  call  the 
intellectual  love  of  God."3 

This  love  is  nothing  more  than  the  sentiment 
which  accompanies  the  conception  of  a  universal 
necessity,  accepted,  not  without  resignation,  as  if  it 
w-ere  a  question  of  an  odious  fatalism,  but  with 
pleasure  because  the  reason  is  satisfied.  Is  not  such 
a  moral  philosophy  of  superhuman  grandeur  ? 4 

1  Spinoza,  V.,  Prop,  xxiji.      -  Ibid.,  Schol.       3  Ibid.,  Coroll.  xxxii. 
4  Guyau,  La  Morale  d? Epicure,  "  Mais  cet  amour,  au  fond,  n'a  rien 
de  libre;  c'est  une  necessite,"  p.  236. — TR. 


THE   ETHICS   OF   SPINOZA. 

It  presents  itself,  however,  in  all  Spinoza's  work  as 
an  ethic  of  great  social  influence,  since  the  amor  Dei 
intcllectualis,  the  love  of  pure  reason,  appears  to  us  as 
alone  capable  of  uniting  men  who  are  divided  by 
their  individual  interests  and  passions.1  Spinoza's 
politics  are  a  legitimate  development  of  his  morality. 
The  degree  of  morality  required  for  the  soul  to 
become  immortal  is  not  therefore  proposed  as  an 
inaccessible  ideal;  Spinoza  believed  in  the  possibility 
of  realising  in  human  nature  his  conception  of  the 
virtuous  being.  It  may  be  surprising  that  the 
thinker  who  has  so  skilfully  analysed  the  passions 
of  man,  who,  no  doubt,  experienced  them  with  in- 
tensity, should  have  attributed  to  pure  love  of  the 
universal  reason  so  great  a  power.  But  we  must 
never  forget  that  Spinoza  is  an  inflexible  logician, 
absorbed  in  demonstrations  more  geometrico,  who, 
when  once  a  principle  is  laid  down,  follows  it  up  to 
its  remotest  consequences  without  troubling  himself 
about  their  agreement  with  reality. 

From  the  tendency  of  the  being  to  persevere  in  his 
being,  joined  with  the  belief,  which  in  his  opinion  is 
false,  that  others  can  favour  or  oppose  this  essential 
tendency — from  this  he  derives  all  the  passions, 
and  from  this  in  the  same  way  he  deduces  all 
"actions,"  all  morality,  and  every  fundamental 
"  conatus,"  joined  to  the  idea  that  God  is  the  sole 
and  eternal  agent.  And  thus  Spinoza  does  not 
trouble  himself  with  human  nature;  he  pursues  his 
long  series  of  demonstrations,  corollaries,  and  scholia 
after  having  by  a  stroke  of  the  pen  substituted  pure 
reason  for  the  passionate  nature  of  man.  And  that 
is  why  his  Ethics  is  at  once  so  beautiful  and  so  use- 

1   Vide  above,  sect.  41,  p.  77.— TR. 


120  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

less;    it   is   one    of    those   noble   works   which   win 
admirers  but  not  disciples. 

To  require  men  to  renounce  their  natural  senti- 
ments and  to  devote  themselves  either  to  the  dis- 
interested contemplation  of  the  true,  as  Plato  and 
Aristotle  required,  or  to  the  love  of  God,  of  Humanity, 
or  of  reason,  is  quite  obviously  to  demand  a  super- 
human effort.  All  the  spring^  of  the  soul  are  broken 
in  a  state  of  extreme  tension;  or  rather,  there  is 
nothing  left  but  illusion,  self-dupery  in  a  sham 
morality. 

60.  The  Stoic  Morality. 

Nor  is  normal  systematisation  best  assured  by 
those  moral  theories  which  develop  to  excess  analo- 
gous sentiments. 

Stoicism  is  a  doctrine  of  excessive  tension  (TOVOS) 
against  everything  which  may  appear  indulgence  to 
human  nature.  Epicurus  attained  a  kind  of  asceti- 
cism from  an  excessive  desire  for  apathy;  in  their 
search  for  impassiveness  the  Stoics  eventually  de- 
spised pain,  and  even  brought  themselves  into  the 
mental  attitude  of  the  martyrs;  their  love  of  virtue 
led  them  to  the  conclusion  that  it  is  nowhere  to  be 
found. 

We  must  not  be  led  astray  by  their  maxim,  ffiv 
o/ioAoyov/zei/o)^  which  was  very  rapidly  completed  by 
the  disciples  of  Cleanthes,  if  not,  indeed,  by  Cleanthes 
himself,  o/xoAoyoiy/ei'ODs  TYJ  (f>v<T€i  ^v.  For  it  is  not  a 
question  with  them  of  living  according  to  human 
nature,  but  rather  according  to  the-  rule  which 
governs  all  nature,  the  Aoyo§  immanent,  at  the  same 
time  both  reason  and  providence,  which  is  the 


THE    STOIC    MORALITY.  121 

principle  of  order  in  the  universe,  and  should  be 
in  man  the  principle  of  that  order,  that  harmony, 
and  that  beauty  in  which  virtue  essentially  consists. 
"  Our  own  natures  are  parts  of  universal  nature,  our 
end  is  therefore  to  live  conformably  to  nature."1 

To  introduce  the  least  disorder  into  the  universe  is 
to  be  vicious,  and  in  vice,  as  in  virtue,  there  are  no 
degrees.  "A  man  in  the  water  does  not  drown  any 
more  at  six  feet  deep  than  at  six  hundred  below  the 
surface  of  the  water."  The  recognition  of  a  possible 
progress  towards  the  highest  virtue,  a  progress  which 
was  already  the  sign  of  a  virtuous  nature,  was  a  tardy 
improvement  of  the  doctrine.  The  wise  man  could 
not  have  one  virtue  without  having  them  all.  But 
where  are  we  to  find  that  wise  man  ? 

All  men,  then,  were  "  mad,  impious,  and  slaves," 
for  the  Stoics  themselves  confessed  that  they  had 
never  seen  their  ideal  realised.  This  was  because  the 
wise  man  ought  not  only  to  have  all  the  virtues,  to  be 
"  the  sole  just  and  pious  man,  the  sole  priest,  the 
sole  savant  and  poet,  the  friend,  citizen,  general,  magis- 
trate, orator,  dialectician,  and  grammarian "  par 
excellence,  but  he  ought  also  to  experience  no  passion, 
for  passion  is  an  "irrational  movement  of  the  soul,  a 
stormy  and  immoderate  impulse,  contrary  to  nature," 
from  which  the  virtuous  being  is  exempt  because  he 
is  infallible.2 

No  doubt  there  were  noble  affections  which  the 
Stoics  admired — joy,  rational  elevation  as  opposed 
to  pleasure,  circumspection  and  will — but  the  ideal 
state  was  none  the  less  in  their  eyes  impassivity,  the 
absence  of  all  abandonment  to  pleasure  or  pain,  and 

1  Renouvier,  Manuel  de  Philosophic  ancienne,  t.  ii.  p.  282. 

2  Cf.  Diogenes,  Life  of  Zeno,  vii.  108-118. 


122  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

they  did  not  desire  to  experience  happiness  except 
under  abnormal  tension. 

Pity  seems  to  have  been  unknown  to  them ;  they 
praised  friendship  and  practised  it ;  they  gave  noble 
examples  of  devotion  and  solidarity;  and  we  cannot 
forget  that  it  was  one  of  the  last  of  the  Stoics  who 
called  himself  a  citizen  of  the  world,  extending  his 
affection  to  the  whole  human  race ;  but  there  was  in 
primitive  Stoicism  the  unmistakable  sign  of  appalling 
hardness  of  heart.  How  many  forms  of  good  were 
there  on  which  the  sage  cast  a  disdainful  glance? 
How  many  evils  did  he  consider  negligible  ?  Does 
pain  depend  on  us  ?  If  it  is  not  in  our  power  to 
avoid  it,  or  to  cause  it  to  cease,  it  is  therefore 
a  matter  of  indifference  to  us,  it  does  not  count: 
we  need  pay  no  attention  to  it.  "The  exist- 
ence of  all  so-called  evils  is  explained  by  the 
necessities  of  organisation  and  life.  These  are  all 
circumstances  connected  with  the  great  final  causes 
of  the  universe,  and  are  therefore  as  such  indifferent 
to  the  sage." 

This  optimism,  which  sometimes  had  such  tragical 
consequences,  has  some  grandeur  about  it.  It  is  a 
false  grandeur  nevertheless,  like  that  of  the  man 
who  does  not  wish  his  poverty  to  be  seen.  That 
psychology  is  erroneous  which  refuses  to  recognise 
that,  in  many  cases,  emotions  and  tendencies  are 
normal  facts  of  the  mental  life.  It  arbitrarily 
demands  of  human  nature  impossible  sacrifices. 

61.  The  ^Esthetic  Sentiment. 

The  Stoics  seem  to  have  always  given  to  their 
doctrine  the  attraction  which  a  conception,  that  has 


THE    AESTHETIC    SENTIMENT.  123 

for  its  centre  the  idea  of  the  beautiful,  always  has  on 
the  human  mind.  They  had  conceived  of  the  uni- 
verse as  an  admirable  order,  as  a  reality  full  of 
harmony  and  finality,  in  which  the  human  mind 
aesthetic  joy;  was  it  not  inevitable  that  man,  in  a 
could  find  a  thousand  motives  of  astonishment  and 
spirit  of  what  one  may  almost  call  sulkiness,  should 
have  attempted  to  destroy  this  marvellous  totality  ? 
Madman  had  been  he  who,  refusing  to  conform  to 
the  natural  law,  was  compelled  by  an  effort  which 
was  against  reason,  and  therefore  powerless,  to  destroy 
a  divine  and  eternal  harmony.  Rarely  since  the 
days  of  Zeno,  Cleanthes,  and  Chrysippus,  have  the 
moralists  had  a  tendency  so  marked  to  associate 
closely  the  ideas  of  the  good  and  the  beautiful. 
Kant,  however,  made  of  the  aesthetic  sentiment,  the 
resultant  of  a  spontaneous  agreement  of  the  sensi- 
bility and  the  understanding,  a  preparation,  as  it 
were,  for  the  moral  sentiment.  And  it  seems  that 
he  was  right  when  he  saw  in  aesthetics  the  "anti- 
chamber"  of  morality.1  The  sense  of  the  beautiful 
may,  no  doubt,  be  produced  independently  of  every 
moral  sentiment.  All  that  is  beautiful  is  not  satisfy- 
ing to  our  conscience.  Art  aims  at  cultivating  senti- 
ments, which,  to  be  disinterested,  in  comparison  with 
hedonistic  and  utilitarian  tendencies,  are  none  the 
less  more  akin  to  satisfactions  of  the  intelligence 
than  to  moral  satisfaction.  A  work  of  art,  or  a 
natural  phenomenon  worthy  of  admiration,  appeals 
especially  to  the  imagination  and  to  the  reason; 
to  the  one  they  give  a  free  course  in  the  field  of  the 
concrete,  connected  with  the  present  perception  and 

1  Cf.   Ruskin,  Sesame  and  Lilies,  "Taste  is  not  only  a  part  and  an 
index  of  morality  ;  it  is  the  only  morality." — TR. 


124  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

the  idea  at  first  evoked;  to  the  other  they  allow  its 
favourite  occupation — synthesis,  "  subsumption,"  as 
Kant  called  it,  of  a  multiplicity  of  data  under  the 
unity  of  the  concept  and  of  the  multiplicity  of  con- 
cepts under  the  unity  of  the  principle.  Thus  they 
procure  for  us  the  pleasure  of  amusement,  of  human 
amusement  par  excellence,  unknown  to  animals  because 
they  have  not  a  reason  sufficiently  exercised  to  ex- 
perience the  pleasure  of  disentangling  ideas,  and  of 
giving  them  the  richest  possible  sensible  expression. 
But  in  direct  relation  with  conduct  is  the  character 
of  the  "  communicability "  of  aesthetic  impressions 
and  pleasures.  Guyau  put  it  very  well  when 
he  said:  "When  I  see  the  beautiful  I  want  to 
be  two."1  The  enjoyment  that  one  experiences  in 
the  contemplation  of  a  work  of  art  is  one  of  those 
very  rare  enjoyments  which  we  love  to  share  with 
others,  or  to  experience  in  common.  The  more 
numerous  are  those  who  share  in  an  emotion  of  this 
kind,  the  deeper  it  is  in  each,  and  that  because  of  the 
repercussion  of  the  emotions  of  others  in  oneself. 
Then  is  produced  in  fact  one  of  those  phenomena  of 
sympathy  which  are  the  point  of  departure  of  a  new 
order  of  tendencies — the  altruistic  tendencies.2 


62.  The  Altruistic  Tendencies? 

Sympathy  in  its  rudimentary  form  is  nothing  more 
than  a  physiological  and  mental  adaptation  to  a  fact 

1  Cf.  Guyau,  Problemes  de  V  Esthelique  Contemporaine. — TR. 

2  Cf.  Ribot,  op.  «'/.,  chap,  x.— TR. 

3  Ribot,  op.  cit.,  chap,  iv.,  "On  the  different  and  conflicting  degrees 
of  altruism;"  vide  Sorley,  op.  cit.,  p.  143. — TR. 


THE    ALTRUISTIC    TENDENCIES.  125 

of  emotional  expression  in  another.1  The  animal  is 
not  incapable  of  experiencing  its  effects;  man  ex- 
periences them  much  more  keenly  because  his  mind 
is  simpler,  and  his  spontaneous  reactions  are  less 
obstructed  or  inhibited  by  reflection  or  by  counter 
associations  of  an  empirical  origin.  In  the  presence 
of  a  being  exhibiting  keen  pleasure  or  pain,  the 
intelligent  and  "naive"  animal  (if  I  may  use  this  word 
of  the  being  in  whom  are  absent  the  "  antagonistic 
reductives,"  which  ordinarily  place  an  obstacle  in  the 
way  of  suggestibility  or  credulity)  permits  its  clear 
consciousness  to  be  invaded  by  the,  from  that 
moment,  very  lively  representation  of  the  emotion 
of  another;  and  in  virtue  of  the  well-known  law  in 
accordance  with  which  the  preponderant  image  pro- 
duces the  realisation  of  the  corresponding  move- 
ment or  system  of  movements,  we  see  the  spectator 
of  the  pain  of  a  fellow-creature  either  betray  signs 
of  similar  pain,  or,  at  any  rate,  place  himself  where 
he  can  avoid  the  cause  of  the  pain.  In  the  same 
way  he  who  is  present  at  the  experience  of  another's 
joy,  if  he  is  a  simple  soul  in  whom  jealous  senti- 
ments have  not  made  their  appearance,  cannot  fail  to 
share  that  pleasure,  even  although  he  may  not  know 
why  his  fellow  is  rejoicing.  Many  acts  of  devotion 
and  of  heroic  self-sacrifice  are  due  to  a  sympathy 
as  instinctive  as  it  is  elementary.  How  many  men 
throw  themselves  into  danger,  blindly  and  without 
reflection,  to  help  beings  whom  they  do  not  know, 
who  have  never  inspired  them  with  affection,  simply 
from  the  effect  of  the  sympathetic  impulse ! 2 

1  Lloyd  Morgan,  Introduction  to  Comparative  Psychology,  p.    32*  > 
ib..  Psychology  for  Teacher s>  p.  234 ;  James,  op.  cit..  ii.  pp.  410, 411. — TR. 
-  Ribot,  op.  cit.)  chap,  iv. 


126  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

At  this  first  stage,  at  least,  there  are  really  no 
altruistic  tendencies;  there  are  only  disinterested 
impulses.  Whatever  La  Rochefoucauld1  and  his 
disciples  may  say,  real  disinterestedness  exists; 
but  it  is  sometimes  prior  to  every  calculation  and 
reflection,  spontaneous,  and  almost  unjustifiable  by 
the  light  of  cool  reason.  All  that  education  can 
do  is  to  strengthen  it  by  declaring  it  in  conformity 
with  certain  exigencies  of  practical  reason.  The 
development  of  the  intellect  tends  on  the  contrary  to 
eliminate  it,  to  replace  it  by  a  fundamentally  egoistic 
calculation  of  the  interest  that  one  may  have  in 
doing  good  to  others,  of  the  advantages  that  one 
may  expect  for  oneself  if  one  shows  oneself  dis- 
interested. 

The  love  of  others  does  not  become  a  tendency 
really  distinct  both  from  primitive  sympathy  and 
the  egoism  developed  by  reflection,  until  the  age  of 
puberty,  when  there  is  in  the  organism  what  we 
may  call  an  overflow  of  energy,  an  excess  of  vitality. 
The  necessity  of  self-sacrifice  without  selfish  after- 
thought is  then  clear.  That  is  the  moment  of 
chivalrous  enterprises,  of  generous  dreams,  of  illusions 
which  are  sometimes  ridiculous,  of  hopes  which 
are  sometimes  chimerical — illusions  and  hopes 
which  always  denote  something  more  than  serene 
self-confidence,  and  the  keenest  desire  of  living 
the  widest  and  the  most  complete  social  life  that 
is  possible.2 

Sexual  love   is   only  a  means  to  a  higher  end — 

1  II  y  a  quelque  chose  dans  les  malheurs  de  nos  meilleurs  amis  qui 
ne  nous  deplait  pas, — Proverb. — TR. 

2  Cf.    Mercier,    Sanity  and  Insanity,  pp.    208-212;    Chamberlain, 
The  Child:  A  Study  in  the  Evolution  of  Man,  pp.  411-415. — TR. 


GENEROSITY.  127 

procreation,  and  the  love  of  children.  When  the 
man  has  reached  the  stage  of  gathering  a  family 
around  him,  he  no  longer  lives  for  himself  but  for 
his  belongings,  and  in  his  devotion  at  all  times  to 
those  who  are  nearest  and  dearest  to  him  he  is 
going  through  the  apprenticeship  to  social  life  with 
its  implied  devotion  to  the  collective  interest. 

Thus  the  social  tendencies  have  two  principles  in 
the  individual  nature,  spontaneous  sympathy  and 
love,  impulses  and  needs  which  are  each  of  a  psycho- 
physiological  nature,  and  can  only  lead  to  failure 
in  the  case  of  abnormal  or  incomplete  beings. 
The  development  of  the  social  tendencies  produces 
the  spirit  of  family,1  the  spirit  of  association,  the 
spirit  of  sect,  civic  virtues,  urbanity,  patriotism, 
humanitarian  aspirations,  noble  political  passions, 
etc. — varied  sentiments  which  play  the  most  im- 
portant role  in  moral  deliberation,  and  which  are 
most  often  in  opposition  to  the  egoistic  tendencies,  to 
the  preservation  and  development  of  the  individual 
being,  tendencies  themselves  opposed  to  one  an- 
other in  so  far  as  they  are  defensive  or  offensive, 
conservative  or  reforming. 

The  complete  development  of  the  social  senti- 
ments takes  us  farther  and  farther  away  from  selfish 
individualism. 

63.  Generosity. 

To  live  with  one's  fellow-creatures,  and  to  get 
from  them  as  much  as  one  can,  and  to  pay  them  as 
little  as  possible  in  return,  is  the  aim  of  the  intel- 

1  But  vide  Ribot,  op.  cit.  p.  285:  "A  high  development  of  the  social 
tendencies  has  only  been  possible  through  the  suppression  of  the  family 
tendencies. " — TR. 


128  THE   MORAL  TENDENCIES. 

ligent  egoist,  of  the  man  who  has  grasped  the  idea 
that  we  can  only  secure  happiness  for  ourselves  in 
a  society  by  making  some  sacrifices  to  the  interests 
of  others :  such  a  man  carefully  calculates  what  his 
devotion  to  the  public  good,  and  what  the  services 
he  renders  to  his  fellow-creatures,  will  bring  him  in 
return,  and  he  does  nothing  for  which  he  will  not 
receive  an  equivalent ;  he  is  well  armed  for  the 
fray,  but  he  lacks  something  that  is  human — 
generosity.1 

Guyau,2  from  a  purely  naturalistic  standpoint, 
clearly  saw  that  "  life  has  two  faces :  on  the  one 
hand  it  is  nutrition  and  assimilation,  on  the  other 
production  and  fecundity.  .  .  .  To  spend  on  others 
what  the  social  life  demands,  is  not,  when  all  is 
said  and  done,  an  individual  loss;  it  is  a  desirable 
aggrandisement  and  even  a  necessity.  The  object  of 
life  is  radiation."  Egoism  corresponds  to  nutrition 
and  altruism  to  reproduction ;  there  is  perhaps  even 
more  than  a  correspondence :  the  need  of  assimila- 
tion dominates  the  whole  sphere  of  economics ; 
it  is  this  need  which  induces  man  to  employ 
himself  in  every  kind  of  industry,  which  leads 
to  competition  and  discord ;  but  the  need  of  re- 
production, of  child-bearing,  of  giving,  of  radiating, 
comes  from  the  very  first  to  counterbalance 
the  effects  of  the  other  natural  need ;  and  it  is  that 
which  has,  in  the  origin  of  civilisation,  been  the 
cause  of  games  and  holidays,  and  from  which  has 
arisen  art  and  religion ;  this  it  is  which  gives  rise  to 
animal  and  human  sociability. 

M.    Espinas  has  shown   how   "  animal  societies " 

1  Spencer,  Principles  of  Psychology,  chap.  viii. 

2  Esquisse  d^une  morale  sans  obligation  ni  sanction,, — TK. 


GENEROSITY.  I2Q 

founded  on  the  instinct  of  reproduction,  on  the 
care  to  be  given  in  common  to  the  young,  may  in 
many  respects  be  compared  with  human  societies. 
Love,  in  its  origin,  is  pure  disinterestedness,  ab- 
negation, joy  in  spontaneous,  natural,  irreflective 
sacrifice.  Sexual  love  is  the  very  antithesis  of 
utilitarian  calculation.  Paternal  or  maternal  love 
in  animals  is  even  quite  the  opposite  of  egoistic 
prudence.  Civilisation  has  no  doubt,  side  by  side 
with  the  power  of  reflection,  developed  in  humanity 
self-love  and  the  tendency  to  make  of  oneself  the  centre 
of  the  universe ;  but  to  an  ignorant  reflection  which 
encourages  a  foolish  pride,  we, may  more  and  more 
oppose  a  scientific  reflection  which  discloses  to  man 
his  insignificance  and  makes  him  conscious  of  his 
vanity.  What  thinker  who,  realising  his  lack  of 
influence  on  the  world,  his  humble  origin,  what- 
ever is  accidental  in  his  success,  or  illusory  in 
the  gratification  he  experiences  in  "  believing  himself 
to  be  some  one,"  does  not  feel  himself  bound  to 
surrender  an  unjustified  egoism  ?  Does  not  much 
knowledge  restore  to  us  what  a  little  knowledge 
takes  from  us — a  proper  humility  and  a  greater 
respect  for  others?  If -we  do  not  allow7  ourselves 
to  be  misled  by  a  false  conception  of  our  ego,  we 
find  generous  sentiments  spontaneously  growing 
within  us,  which  urge  us  to  help  others,  to  give 
without  the  hope  of  return,  and  to  sacrifice 
ourselves  without  the  hope  of  reward.  And  in  pro- 
portion as  we  attain  a  higher  degree  of  mental  de- 
velopment we  begin  to  feel  a  desire  for  expenditure, 
uncalculated  action,  and  disinterested  activity. 

As  Guyau1  says,   "There  is  in  lofty  pleasures  a 

1  Op.  cit. 


130  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

force  of  expansion  ever  ready  to  pierce  the  envelope  of 
our  ego.  In  their  presence  we  feel  we  are  insufficient 
to  ourselves,  and  only  act  in  order  to  transmit  them, 
just  as  the  vibrating  atom  of  the  ether  gradually 
transmits  the  ray  of  the  sidereal  light  which  crosses 
it,  and  of  which  it  retains  nothing  but  a  transient 
vibration.  It  is  our  whole  being  that  is  sociable ; 
life  does  not  recognise  the  absolute  classifications 
and  divisions  of  the  metaphysicians  and  logicians; 
our  being  cannot,  even  if  it  desired,  be  completely 
egoistic." 

64.  Sociability.1 

The  force  of  vital  expansion  is  thus  the  natural 
foundation  of  sociability ;  the  modifications  of  this 
force  constitute  the  generous  sentiments  which  cause 
men  to  become  not  only  "  invading  but  invaded," 
which  prevent  them  from  remaining  content  with 
the  maximum  of  assimilation,  which  induce  them  to 
refrain  from  appropriating  for  their  own  benefit  the 
greatest  amount  of  good,  and  assuring  for  themselves 
the  greatest  number  of  advantages ;  as  soon  as  they 
feel  themselves  in  possession  of  some  joy,  some  good, 
or  some  advantage,  they  endeavour  to  communicate 
it  to  their  fellow-creatures  and  to  share  it  with  them. 
"  We  have  more  tears  than  we  need  for  our  own 
sufferings,  and  more  joys  in  reserve  than  our  own 
happiness  justifies."  2  Only  depressed,  congenitally 
weak,  and  impotent  beings  fall  back  on  themselves; 
they  have  no  more  energy  than  is  needed  for  their 

1  For  Guyau's  doctrine  of  the  expansion  of  life  as   a   principle   of 
ethics,   art,   and  religion,    vide   Fouillee,    La   Morale,    L'Arf,   et  La 
Religion  d'Apres  M.    Gziyau,   and    The    Westminster  Review,    April 
1892,  pp.  394  et  seq. 

2  Guyau,  op.  cit. 


SOCIABILITY.  131 

own  subsistence ;  they  are  always  suffering  from  a 
want  of  vital  energy,  and  therefore  lack  sociability. 
But  in  all  those  to  whom  good  health  and  vigour 
permit  a  normal  life  we  see  generosity  increase  and 
decrease  with  the  exuberance  and  harmony  of  the 
vital  processus.  The  more  pleasant  life  is,  the  greater 
is  jo}7,  and  the  greater  also  is  generosity. 

The  normal  man  is  therefore  generous,  and  ipso 
facto  he  begins  to  be  a  social  being.  But  more  is 
required.  Sociability  is  not  only  the  aptitude  to 
live  with  one's  fellows,  and  to  share  in  common 
one's  prosperity,  advantages,  troubles,  and  joys.  It 
is  also  an  aptitude  to  submit  oneself  to  a  common 
rule,  and  to  live  a  regular  life  according  to  the 
prescriptions  imposed  upon  all  by  all. 

Perhaps  I  have  not  hitherto  insisted  sufficiently 
on  this  mark  of  sociability  which  springs  from  an 
essentially  rational  tendency.  There  are  in  society 
two  opposite  tendencies,  the  one  to  imitation,  the 
other  to  innovation.  If  we  wish  to  explain  in  a 
satisfactory  manner  the  synergy  of  individual 
changes  from  the  point  of  view  of  collective 
modification,  we  must  place  above  these  general 
appetitions  a  tendency  to  impose  on  others,  and  to 
accept  from  others  rules  of  common  and  even  of 
individual  conduct. 

In  fact,  what  are  the  beings  who  do  not  re- 
cognise the  authority  of  such  rules,  who  are  always 
in  a  state  of  revolt  against  all  authority,  and  profess 
to  obey  themselves  alone — i.e.,  to  follow  their  own 
caprices?  They  are  the  diseased,  the  unstable, 
those  who  have  no  self-control,  who  are  without 
the  inhibitive  force  which  enables  them  to  co- 
ordinate their  tendencies  and  to  systematise  their 


132  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

different  states  of  consciousness.  They  are  con- 
sidered unsociable,  not  simply  because  they  do  not 
submit  themselves  to  the  domination  of  law  and  rules 
at  present  established  by  the  State  and  the  com- 
munity, but  rather,  and  on  juster  grounds,  because 
they  cannot  bear  the  yoke  of  any  law,  of  any  power, 
even  of  their  own  reason.  They  give  way  in  the 
presence  of  strong  restraint,  but  only  for  a  moment; 
they  imitate,  and  sometimes  very  easily,  but  they 
imitate  in  turn  irreconcilable  models.  Therefore, 
neither  compulsion  nor  imitation  can  give  them 
sociability;  they  lack  a  normal  tendency.  It  goes 
without  saying  that  this  new  aspect  of  sociability, 
due  to  legality,  although  by  itself  it  may  have 
the  effect  of  establishing  the  greatest  uniformity 
in  the  sentiments,  tendencies,  and  acts,  is  not  at 
first  blended  with  the  spirit  of  obedience,  but  is 
much  more  akin  to  mean  servility,  of  complaisance 
to  the  powerful,  whoever  they  may  be,  which  is  a 
sign  of  weakness,  and  is  the  almost  exclusive  mark 
of  the  domestic  animal ;  later,  it  does  not  exclude 
tendencies  to  innovation,  to  freedom  of  mind,  and 
to  action  relatively  original.  It  forbids  eccentricity 
and  unbridled  originality,  which  would  prevent  men 
from  coming  to  a  common  understanding  on  art, 
religion,  politics,  just  as  on  any  other  way  of  looking 
at  the  facts  of  existence  or  of  solving  practical 
questions.  It  is  an  insuperable  obstacle  to  moral 
anarchy,  but  it  must  not  become  a  cause  of  routine 
or  social  stagnation.  It  causes  in  every  environment, 
at  every  stage  of  civilisation,  a  common  spirit  whose 
conceptions  and  artistic  tastes,  whose  fashions  and 
simplest  customs,  ought  to  bear  its  mark ;  but  it 
"must  also  be  reconciled  with  the  first  characteristic 


TENDENCY   TO    SOCIAL   ORGANISATION.  133 

we  have  recognised  in  sociability :  the  characteristic 
of  generosity  which  arises  from  the  tendency  to 
make  our  fellows  share  in  the  pleasure  we  experience, 
the  good  we  enjoy,  and  the  state  of  mind  in  which 
we  are. 

The  spirit  of  obedience  to  a  common  law,  and  of 
conformity  to  collective  prescriptions  may  serve  as 
an  "  antagonistic  reducer  "  to  the  spirit  of  innovation 
\vhich  sometimes  is  the  cause  of  an  unlimited  gene- 
rosity. It  is  only  by  making  the  synthesis  of  the 
two  tendencies  that  \ve  can  attain  the  conception 
of  that  sociability  which  may  henceforth  be  defined 
as  the  aptitude  to  live  in  common  according  to 
the  same  rules,  but  in  such  a  way  as  to  make  all 
share  as  much  as  possible  in  the  advantages  and  the 
joys  which  are  assured  to  each  by  the  degree  of 
perfection  wrhich  each  has  attained. 

65.  Tendency  to  Social  Organisation. 

A  still  higher  degree  of  sociability  may  be  at- 
tained by  the  superior  being  who  feels  within  him- 
self enough  force,  talent,  and  energy  to  devote 
himself  to  the  work  of  social  organisation. 

We  might  take  up  again,  with  considerable  modi- 
fication, the  Leibnitzian  conception  of  a  perfect  being, 
organising  the  world  in  such  a  way  that  the  greatest 
harmony  of  the  greatest  number  of  elements  is  the 
result.  It  is  enough  to  transpose  from  the  divine  to 
the  human  this  idea  of  creative  activity ;  to  say  that 
each  of  us,  in  so  far  as  we  are  reasonable,  aspires  to 
become  the  organiser  par  excellence ;  that  the  aim  of 
moral  activity  is  in  truth  of  the  architectonic  order ; 
is  it  not  therefore  natural  to  conceive  of  the  obliga- 


134  THE    MORAL   TENDENCIES. 

tion  to  labour,  like  so  many  terrestrial  gods,  in  the 
building  up  of  a  work  whose  scope  is  outside  our 
individual  sphere,  our  environment,  and  our  age  ? 

The  most  intelligent  child  in  the  village  endea- 
vours to  organise  the  heterogeneous  band  of  his 
companions;  not  only  does  he  try,  as  so  many 
psychological  moralists  have  pointed  out,  to  im- 
pose the  same  rule  of  games  upon  all,  to  submit 
all  to  a  strict  observation  of  certain  principles  of 
conduct,  but  he  forces  himself  to  govern,  to  dis- 
tribute the  functions  and  roles,  to  co-ordinate, 
organise,  and  systematise.1  Adults  do  the  same. 
The  whole  of  humanity  has  ever  been  in  search 
of  an  organising  power  from  the  earliest  moment 
of  its  existence  as  a  reasoning  species.  Govern- 
ments are  not  artificial  organs,  the  arbitrary  crea- 
tions of  the  imagination,  "inventions"  which  might 
never  have  been  "happened  on";  the  idea  of  govern- 
ment, inseparable  from  that  of  conduct,  rule,  or  moral 
law,  is  one  of  the  fundamental  data  of  practical  reason. 

The  duty  of  organising  human  society  and  of 
systematising  social  life  was  observed  before  it  was 
known.  This  duty  appears  more  and  more  to  every 
reasonable  being  as  incumbent  not  on  this  or  that 
member  of  the  social  body  in  particular,  but  on  every 
member  of  the  sovereign  body,  that  is  to  say  on  every 
citizen. 

To  sum  up,  we  see  superimposed  on  tendencies 
to  pleasure,  happiness,  and  individual  and  collective 
utility,  tendencies  to  intellectual  and  aesthetic 
pleasure  ;  and  finally  sociability,  a  complex  tendency 
which  embraces  altruism,  the  spirit  of  sacrifice, 
the  spirit  of  solidarity,  of  discipline,  of  obedience 

1  Vide  Chamberlain,  op.  cif.,  chap.  ii. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  IDEAL  AND  MORAL  FIRMNESS.    135 

to  laws  and  to  generous  innovation.  All  these 
tendencies,  far  from  being  incompatible,  form  a 
system  in  the  moral  being. 


IV. 

THE  MORAL  INDIVIDUAL. 

66.  The  Psychological  Ideal  and  Moral  Firmness. 

A  man  cannot  be  fully  moral  if  he  does  not  realise 
the  psychological  ideal  in  the  widest  possible  measure. 
But  to  attain  this  higher  degree,  viz.,  morality,  he 
must  begin  by  having  a  healthy  mind. 

Now  normal  systematisation  consists  in  the  stability 
of  certain  tendencies  which  do  not  prevent  the  ap- 
pearance of  others,  but  which  give  to  them  as  it 
were  the  characteristic  colouring  of  the  person  who 
manifests  them,  and  which  in  particular  bring  it  about 
that  the  successive  appetitions  of  an  individual  form 
a  continuous  series,  the  different  terms  of  which  are 
closely  linked  together,  and  in  some  measure  summon 
one  another.  These  tendencies  which  constitute 
the  essential  character  of  a  being  can  only  be  very 
general,  and  their  object  very  indeterminate.  One 
subject  has  a  more  marked  tendency  than  another 
to  remember  sounds  or  colours  (auditive  or  visual 
types),  to  associate  ideas  by  contrast  or  resemblance, 
to  experience  violent  or  joyful  emotions,  and  to 
act  slowly  or  quickly;  but  such  features  of  the 
character,  if  they  sometimes  predispose  rather  to 
activity  than  to  speculation,  to  art  than  to  science, 
none  the  less  may  not  prevent  us  from  experiencing 
scientific  or  artistic  pleasure  as  well  as  happiness 


136  THE    MORAL    INDIVIDUAL. 

in  certain  social,  friendly,  or  family  relations.  If 
they  cause  attention  to  be  attracted  to  and  to  be 
maintained  on  objects  of  art  rather  than  on  con- 
ceptions, or  on  business,  they  do  not  prevent  the 
mind  from  understanding  arguments,  from  finding 
pleasure  in  discussion,  in  deduction,  or  in  absorption 
in  affairs. 

What  is  of  importance  to  the  normal  develop- 
ment of  the  mental  functions  is,  that  there  shall  be 
no  breaches  of  continuity  in  the  mental  activity, 
breaches  due  to  a  juxtaposition  of  successive 
tendencies  or  inclinations  without  a  mutual  bond. 
Now  the  succession  of  states  of  consciousness  is  by 
itself,  and  by  itself  alone,  the  source  of  lively 
satisfaction,  of  psychological  pleasure,  if  we  may 
s<iy  so,  when  it  is  effected  without  violence  or 
sudden  shock,  by  a  sort  of  interpenetration  of  the 
sentiments  which  takes  place  in  the  unoccupied 
consciousness.  Is  not  this  pleasure  the  index  of 
the  normal  state  par  excellence,  and  ought  it  not 
to  be  sought  by  the  moral  agent,  and  in  the  first 
place  from  the  point  of  view  of  his  personal  satis- 
faction, in  so  far  as  he  is  a  purely  psychic  being  ? 

For  its  production,  a  certain  firmness  is  required. 
In  fact  what  usually  is  harmful  to  mental  continuity  is 
that  the  mind  is  given  up  defenceless  to  every  kind 
of  influence,  buffeted  in  every  direction,  incapable 
of  introducing  order  into  its  representations,  of 
effecting  complete  syntheses,  of  following  an  argu- 
ment, or  of  maintaining  in  predominance  certain 
tendencies;  of  avoiding  the  violent  emotions  and 
the  painful  and  disturbing  sentiments,  which  are 
the  "emotion-shocks"  of  which  Dr.  Janet  has  so 
clearly  shown  the  dissolving  power. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  IDEAL  AND  MORAL  FIRMNESS.    137 

When  the  tendencies  are  closely  grouped  they 
oppose  every  mental  disturbance  as  a  permanent 
obstacle,  they  give  to  thought,  to  sensibility,  and 
to  activity,  a  solid  foundation ;  the  individual  be- 
comes master  of  himself  and  has  a  strong  character. 

Nothing  is  therefore  more  necessary  than  firmness 
of  character  (and  therefore  strength  of  will)  for  the 
normal  adaptation  of  the  being  to  its  environment. 

"  Morality  is  the  person  itself;  therefore  we  al- 
ready find  traces  of  it — I  mean  the  elements  and 
the  foundation — in  a  rich  strong  nature,  in  what 
one  calls  a  temperament,  a  character.  On  the 
other  hand  a  mobile  nature,  impressionable  and 
vivacious,  that  is  attracted  by  contrary  emotions  in 
different  directions,  a  mind  without  consistence  and 
without  foundation,  mens  mojnentanea,  lacks  moral 
aptitudes.  It  must  be  absolved  from  evil,  but  we 
must  also  refuse  to  it  the  attribute  of  good.  There 
is  therefore  a  natural  morality,  the  conformity  of 
tendencies  to  some  restraint,  whatever  it  may  be, 
or  simply  to  their  constancy."  * 

While  the  monomaniac  is  led  to  create  for  himself 
an  imaginary  world  in  which  he  thinks  he  lives,  and 
which  prevents  him  from  feeling  keenly  the  sufferings 
involved  in  his  lack  of  adaptation  to  his  environment, 
and  while  the  stubborn  man  is  unhappy  because  he 
does  not  know  how  to  vary  his  circumstances,  the 
man  who  is  gifted  with  a  strong  will  reacts  on  ex- 
ternal stimuli  in  an  appropriate  manner,  although 
his  reactions  always  bear  the  mark  of  his  character ; 
the  course  of  his  states  of  consciousness  loses  none  of 
its  continuity,  although  the  external  circumstances 
vary,  and  that,  even  when  they  are  modified  in  the 

1  Cf.  Dugas,  Revtie  Philosophique  (1897),  t.  xliv.  p.  398. 


138  THE    MORAL    INDIVIDUAL. 

most  quaint  or  unexpected  fashion.  He  it  is  who 
knows  both  how  to  submit  to  circumstances  and 
how  to  utilise  them  for  his  ends.1  Not  only  is  he 
impelled  on  occasion  to  direct  the  course  of  events, 
but  he  lacks  nothing  of  that  indispensable  art  which 
consists  in  bowing  to  the  exigencies  of  the  environ- 
ment ;  instead  of  letting  himself  be  disconcerted  or 
frightened  by  a  rude  shock,  he  takes  time  to  bring 
himself  into  harmony  with  himself  and  with  what  is 
external  to  him. 

And  so  the  moral  being  is  not  accessible  to  fear, 
to  anger,  or  to  those  violent  sentiments  which  betray 
weakness  of  wrill.  He  does  not  experience  those  ex- 
aggerated and  sympathetic  emotions  of  which  a  more 
or  less  delirious  enthusiasm,  and  a  more  or  less  de- 
pressing and  morbid  pity  are  composed,  and  at  the 
same  time  does  not  show  himself  hard  to  others  to 
the  point  of  cruel  and  indifferent  coldness ;  he  keeps 
his  sang-froid  in  the  presence  of  great  pain,  he  knows 
how  to  be  severe  to  those  who  deserve  no  indulgence, 
and  for  whom  love  is  another  name  for  severity.  He 
knows  how  to  keep  himself  from  the  "  moral  con- 
tagion "  which  causes  panics  as  do  .great  waves  of  joy 
or  collective  grief;  far  from  being  impassible  like  the 
Stoics  of  old,  he  lets  himself  go  in  the  presence  of 
joy,  and  he  can  experience  sadness,  but  always  with 
moderation. 

67.  Moderation. 

The  Aristotelian  theory2  of  the  relative  mean 
between  two  extremes  is  based  upon  a  very  exact 

1  Res  niihi,  me  rebus,  submittere  conor  (adapted  quotation). 
-Ethics,   Book   II.,   chap.    ix. ;    Sidgwick,   History  of  Ethics,   pp. 
58,  59--TR. 


MODERATION.  139 

observation  of  the  conditions  of  normal  sensibility. 
For  a  sentiment,  or  for  a  succession  of  sentiments, 
to  produce  pleasure,  the  tendencies,  which  are  among 
the  constituent  elements  of  every  sentiment,  must 
be  strong  enough  to  determine  a  complex  and  well- 
ordinated  psychic  activity.  But  it  is  necessary  in 
addition  that  they  should  not  be  so  violent  as  to 
render  the  subject  insatiable,  devoured  by  desire 
for  impossible  or  unrealisable  gratifications.  They 
must  not  destroy  or  eliminate  other  perfectly  normal 
tendencies,  whose  disappearance  is  not  unaccom- 
panied by  pain.  They  must  therefore  be  counter- 
balanced and  moderated  by  appetitions,  or  by 
contrary  inclinations  which  lack  neither  intensity 
nor  duration.  Voluntary  attention  ought,  if  need  be, 
to  give  these  inhibitive  tendencies  of  violent  passions 
the  intensity  and  the  duration  which  they  lack. 

Temperance  thus  becomes  one  of  the  means  of 
realising  the  normal  psychic  life.  It  is  difficult 
at  first  to  be  temperate  under  all  circumstances ; 
but  self-control,  like  every  other  act,  may  become 
habitual,  and  demand  after  a  lapse  of  time  less 
effort.  We  see  people  in  whom  the  appearance  of 
a  tendency  is  immediately  followed  by  an  effort 
made  in  some  way  to  control  themselves,  not  to 
yield  to  an  appetition  until  after  examination,  and 
that  is  one  of  the  effects  of  a  temperance  which  has 
become  habitual. 

And  this  temperance,  which  engenders  prudence, 
moderation  in  opinion,  and  wise  deliberation  before 
action,  may  always  have  its  inconveniences;  not 
only  may  it  become  distrust,  cowardice,  or  a 
tendency  to  inertia,  if  the  possible  tendencies  to 
eagerness  and  enthusiasm  are  too  energetically 


140  THE    MORAL   INDIVIDUAL. 

opposed,  but  it  also  may  be  harmful  to  those  fine 
impulses  of  courage,  of  confidence,  of  love,  etc.,  which 
are  capable  of  adding  to  the  dignity  of  man,  and  of 
yielding  great  pleasure  without  any  admixture  of 
pain.  Passion  is  not  always  evil,  and  it  has  been 
wrongly  defined  as  perverted  inclination.  There  are 
noble  passions  indispensable  to  the  unfolding  and  to 
the  manifestation  of  genius  and  talent,  and  no  less 
necessary  to  moral  actions  of  the  widest  scope.  Will 
it  be  maintained  that  intellectual  or  moral  genius 
is  an  abnormal  thing  and  akin  to  madness  ?  No 
doubt  many  geniuses  and  many  talented  individuals 
pay  for  their  fertility  by  a  precocious  neurosis.  No 
doubt  mental  over-activity  in  a  particular  domain  is 
injurious  to  mental  equilibrium,  and  may  lead  to 
disorder  in  the  psychic  system ; l  but  there  may 
exist,  or  at  least  one  can  conceive  of  the  existence  of, 
an  exceptional  fertility  of  the  intellect  and  the  will, 
which  is  not  abnormal  and  which  does  not  prevent 
one  from  speaking  of  temperance  in  genius;  for  it 
is  precisely  at  the  moment  when  a  tendency  takes 
exceptional  scope  that  the  greater  need  of  an 
"  antagonist  reducer "  is  felt,  in  order  that  the 
limits  of  the  normal  may  be  attained  without  being 
exceeded,  in  order  that  genial  eagerness  may  not 
become  morbid  excitement,  and  a  fine  passion  may 
not  be  transformed  into  an  acute  mania. 

Temperance  is  therefore  a  quality  of  the  moral 
being,  whether  he  be  an  ordinary  or  a  superior  man ; 

1  Cf.  Grasset,  Conference  sur  le  Ghite  et  la  Nevrose,  Montpellier, 
1899;  Ribot,  op.  cit.,  pp.  360-364,  437  (degeneration  a  necessary  con- 
dition of  high  mental  originality,  "genius  a  neurosis");  Mercier,  op. 
cit.,  p.  181  ;  Fere,  The  Pathology  of  the  Emotions,  chap.  xx. ;  Chamber- 
lain, op.  cit.,  p.  45  ;  Lombroso,  The  Man  of  Genius,  passim. — TR. 


VIRTUE   AND   TRUTH.  141 

it  is  his  first  guarantee  of  continuous  pleasure  and 
happiness. 

But,  like  all  the  other  qualities  which  are  con- 
nected with  strength  of  character,  it  aims  rather  at 
psychological  health  than  at  morality  properly  so 
called.  If  the  latter  has  for  its  necessary  conditions 
the  equilibrium  of  the  mind,  mental  continuity,  the 
cohesion  of  essential  tendencies,  we  cannot  always 
say  that  these  are  the  only  conditions  sufficient  for 
good  conduct.  Remarkable  determination,  excep- 
tional constancy,  perfect  lucidity,  and  a  kind  of 
sanity  of  the  mind  may  be  found  in  crime  and  in 
immorality.  But  the  sanity  of  the  great  criminal, 
wiiose  conduct  is  quite  consistent,  is  the  sanity  of  an 
inferior  mind.  This  being  is  normal  if  we  consider 
it  in  isolation,  and  if  we  judge  it  by  psychological 
criteria;  but  it  is  no  longer  so  if  we  consider  it  from 
the  sociological  and  moral  point  of  view.  In  fact,  it 
lacks  certain  tendencies  whose  dominion  over  the 
mind  assures  the  exact  correspondence  of  the  psychic 
and  moral  health. 

For  a  man  who  is  exempt  from  neuropathic 
troubles  and  from  psycho-pathic  disorder  to  be  a 
moral  being,  he  must  have  certain  habits  of  thought 
and  action  which  reveal  the  constant  play  upon  his 
will  of  higher  tendencies,  of  sentiments  such  as  the 
love  of  the  true  and  the  beautiful,  and  above  all 
of  those  aptitudes  to  life  in  common  to  which  we 
have  given  the  name  of  sociability. 

68.  Virtue  and  Truth. 

.The  moral  virtues  are  the  natural  consequences  of 
the  prominence  in  the  mind  of  these  lofty  appetitions, 


142  THE    MORAL   INDIVIDUAL. 

systematised  in  such  a  way  that  it  is  difficult  to  be 
ruled  by  any  one  of  them  without  being  at  the  same 
time  ruled  by  all  the  others.  The  Stoics  used  to  say 
that  virtue  is  one,1  and  that  if  we  lack  one  moral 
quality  we  lack  them  all.  In  spite  of  the  obvious 
exaggeration  of  this  statement,  they  were  right;  for 
real  morality  only  exists  for  him  who  has  reached 
the  summit  of  a  hierarchy  of  tendencies  and  corre- 
sponding habits,  which  support  one  another  and 
condition  one  another,  both  in  their  appearance 
and  in  their  survival  of  the  effort  that  gave  birth 
to  them. 

We  begin  to  be  virtuous  by  acquiring,  through  the 
proper  exercise  of  the  intellect,  and  through  scientific 
culture,  a  persistent  tendency  to  search  for  truth,  to 
avoid  error,  and  to  detest  falsehood.  The  cult  of  the 
true  is  a  condition  of  morality.  What,  in  fact,  would 
be  the  individual  in  a  perfect  social  system,  who 
should  commit  error,  spread  it  abroad,  act  upon  it, 
and  urge  others  to  act  according  to  erroneous 
maxims  ?  If  he  were  honestly  self-deceived,  he 
would  lack  sanity  from  the  psychological  point  of 
view,  and  we  should  have  to  cure  a  misguided  mind. 
But  if  he  lied,  and  led  others  into  error  knowingly, 
with  persistent  bad  faith,  he  would  constitute 
a  factor  of  trouble,  of  disintegration,  a  morbid 
element  which  would  have  to  be  eliminated  from 
every  community  which  had  for  its  end  moral 
perfection. 

For  error  and  falsehood  are  hostile  to  rational 
systematisation.  Truth  is  one  of  the  ends  of  social 
activity,  because  it  brings  the  thoughts  into  agree- 
ment and  leads  to  the  stable  communion  of  minds. 

1  Mackenzie,  op.  cit.,  p.  222. — TR. 


THE  CULT  OF  THE  BEAUTIFUL.       143 

It  is  also  one  of  the  loftiest  of  the  ends  of  individual 
mental  activity,  because  it  alone  furnishes  a  solid 
basis  of  well  co-ordinated  action,  and  of  action 
that  leads  to  success.  Without  the  possession  of 
truth  the  best  intentions  are  in  vain,  the  will  lacks 
clearness,  conception  and  deliberation  are  deprived 
of  their  normal  bases;  there  is  no  longer  any  moral 
value  in  the  agent,  contrary  to  the  opinion  of  those 
wrho  have  induced  themselves  to  believe  that  inten- 
tion is  in  itself  all  that  is  required. 

69.  The  Cult  oj  the  Beautiful. 

We  acquire  a  higher  degree  of  virtue  when  we 
unite  to  the  love  of  the  true  the  development  of 
aesthetic  sentiments. 

These  sentiments,  at  any  rate  when  they  are  free 
from  admixture  with  the  emotions  and  with  tend- 
encies of  an  inferior  order,  cannot  fail  to  have  a 
happy  influence  on  conduct.  The  search  for  the 
beautiful  is  not  unrelated  to  the  search  for  the 
good,  and  that  is  why  good  actions  are  so  often 
called  beautiful  actions.  No  doubt  there  is  in  this 
terminology  a  possible  confusion,  because  facts  of 
the  moral  order  have  a  particular  beauty  which 
may  arouse  admiration  without  thereby  responding 
to  an  aesthetic  taste;  but  it  is  none  the  less  true 
that  in  many  cases  it  is  because  they  satisfy  our 
desire  for  order,  harmony,  and  beauty,  that  acts 
which  have  a  moral  value  are  declared  beautiful.1 

With  the  exception  of  the  Stoics  and  of  Kant, 
moralists  have  too  rarely  insisted  on  the  moral 
effects  produced  by  the  desire  of  accomplishing 

J  Vide  above,  Section  59. 


144  THE    MORAL    INDIVIDUAL. 

noble  actions  corresponding  to  aesthetic  tendencies, 
and  that  this  desire  may  lead  to  felicitous  results  in 
human  conduct.  Sometimes  there  are  acts  which 
displease  us,  lines  of  conduct  which  are  repugnant 
to  us,  because  a  certain  beauty  is  absent  from  them. 
Moral  rectitude  is  rather  like  a  line  in  architecture 
which  pleases  the  eye  because  it  does  not  demand 
from  it  too  much  effort,  and  because  it  enables  the 
eye  to  embrace  considerable  diversity;  we  like  to  see 
the  development  of  a  series  of  actions  which,  being 
different  and  tending  to  different  ends,  have  never- 
theless a  common  characteristic,  and  in  all  of  which 
the  same  deep  sentiment  is  revealed. 

Disinterestedness  with  respect  to  all  the  material 
advantages  or  ordinary  ends  of  our  actions,  is  often 
only  possible  by  the  aid  of  the  aesthetic  interest 
which  certain  means  or  certain  ends  present  to  us. 
We  then  almost  attain  complete  disinterestedness 
without  however  realising  it.  Besides,  to  realise  it 
would,  no  doubt,  be  pernicious  and  fatal  to  action, 
while  to  approach  so  near  to  it  incontestably  gives  to 
conduct  the  seal  of  an  elevation  pre-eminently  human. 

The  refinement  of  aesthetic  tendencies,  the  purity 
of  corresponding  pleasures,  can  only  contribute  to 
the  refinement  of  the  tendencies  which  determine 
our  action.  To  accustom  one's  self  to  admit  as  far 
as  possible  what  is  really  beautiful  in  contemplation 
and  in  conduct,  and  to  repel  with  energy  that  in 
which  ugliness  causes  a  painful  impression,  was  one 
of  the  first  principles  of  Greek  morality,  of  the 
morality  sanctioned  by  the  most  ancient,  the  most 
free-minded,  and  the  most  attractive  race  of  an- 
tiquity. 

Why  should  the  good  necessarily  assume  an  austere 


THE    CULT   OF   THE    BEAUTIFUL.  145 

aspect  ?  Why  should  we  seek  to  deprive  it  of  every 
attraction,  and  especially  of  that  aesthetic  attraction 
which  only  exists  for  human  nature,  and  is  the 
greater  in  proportion  as  one  appeals  to  the  most 
elevated  minds  ?  The  beautiful  no  doubt  is  not 
always  the  good.  One  may  not  even  trouble  one's 
head  about  the  good  while  admiring  the  beautiful; 
but  why  should  not  the  good  be  beautiful  ?  The 
charitable  act  of  a  man  who  lifts  up  out  of  the  mud 
another  who  is  in  rags,  emaciated,  wounded,  and 
repulsive — would  not  this  act,  if  it  made  part  of  a 
series  of  actions  of  the  same  kind,  attract  our  aesthetic 
sense,  struck  by  the  harmony  which  the  different 
stages  of  this  conduct  present  to  one  another,  and  to 
the  rest  of  the  existence  of  an  honourable  man  ? 

What  is  the  characteristic  of  the  beautiful  ?  To 
give  a  sensible  presentation  of  an  idea  by  exhibiting 
it  as  the  unity  of  the  richest  diversity  of  concrete 
elements — that  is  the  answer  of  Leibnitz,  Kant,  and 
Hegel ;  and  if  the  answer  is  incomplete  it  none 
the  less  furnishes  one  of  the  principal  elements  of 
a  complete  answer.  Now  does  not  conduct  mani- 
fest by  a  diversity  of  concrete  elements,  by  acts,  the 
unity  of  an  idea,  of  a  principle,  of  an  ideal,  and 
ought  it  not  therefore  to  be  always  beautiful  ? 

We  may  add,  if  we  wish,  to  the  response  given  by 
great  philosophers,  the  answer  of  the  psychologists 
and  of  the  sociologists,  who  see  in  the  beautiful  the 
triumph  of  man  over  the  obstacles  placed  in  the  way 
of  the  realisation  of  its  conception, — the  expression  of 
social,  religious,  or  political  ideas,  so  far  as  religion 
and  politics  furnish  the  subject  of  the  commonest 
thought, — the  manifestation  of  original  power  that 
strikes  us  by  the  novelty  of  a  synthesis  which  is  bold 

10 


1:46  THE   MORAL   INDIVIDUAL. 

and  yet  not  too  bold,  and  which  does  not  displease 
us, — the  wealth  and  exuberance  of  life  giving  birth  to 
amusement,  adding  luxury  to  well-being,  generosity 
and  expansion  to  the  struggle  for  existence.  Is  there 
not  something  in  all  these  conceptions  of  art,  held 
by  Spencer,  Guyau,  Tarde,  and  so  many  others, 
that  finds  some  correspondence  in  the  loftiest  moral 
actions,  actions  which  are  the  flower  of  human 
activity  ? 

And  does  not  this  prove  that  the  aesthetic  sen- 
timents ought  to  be  cultivated,  developed,  and 
carried  to  their  highest  degree  of  power  in  the  being 
of  whom  we  wish  to  make  a  moral  agent,  in  order 
that  his  conduct  may  be,  to  the  highest  degree, 
aesthetic  ?  The  sentiment  of  the  beautiful  and  of  the 
sublime  ought  not  therefore  to  be  wanting  to  a  man 
who  is  tending  to  realise  a  human  ideal. 

According  to  M.  Chabot,1  it  is  only  in  the  aesthetic 
conception  of  the  good  that  the  moral  subject  "  may 
be  taken  as  a  whole, — sentiment  and  reason,  imagina- 
tion and  will, — and  may  devote  all  the  forces  of  nature 
to  the  work  of  morality."  A  good  action  is  that 
which  under  the  dominance  of  duty  is  known,  felt, 
and  carried  out  as  the  most  beautiful  possible.  The 
good  man  is  an  artist  who  has  no  right  not  to  be  one. 

But,  as  we  have  seen  on  many  occasions,  he  is  an 
artist  who  is  working  at  a  social  work,  at  a  work  of 
solidarity  which  requires  devotion;  and  displaying 
not  accidental  devotion,  but  constant  sacrifice  of 
himself  to  others.  The  virtues  of  the  father,  the 
mother,  or  the  brother  in  the  family,  those  of  the 
artisan  in  the  workshop  or  in  the  factory,  those  of 
the  citizen  in  the  town  or  in  the  State,  those  of  the 

1  Nature  et  Moralite.     Alcan,  1897. 


JOY.  I47 

individual  in  humanity,  are  greater  in  proportion  as 
the  different  social  functions  are  more  regularly  and 
more  disinterestedly  performed,  with  a  greater  eager- 
ness to  be  aiding  in  a  moral  work,  with  more  success 
in  the  incessant  struggle  against  the  natural  or  arti- 
ficial difficulties  which  are  an  obstacle  in  the  path 
of  human  progress. 

The  moral  being  is  thus,  in  short,  the  man  who 
endeavours  to  preserve  for  himself  or  to  acquire 
health  of  mind,  to  develop  all  his  aptitudes  to  a  wide 
and  fruitful  life,  to  labour  on  behalf  of  social  order, 
and  of  the  complete  aesthetic  and  rational  organisa- 
tion of  humanity.  This  being  is  virtuous,  and  he 
deserves  happiness. 


70.  Joy. 

We  ought  in  fact  to  give  to  joy  and  happiness  a 
place  in  moral  activity.  Man  cannot  give  up  joy 
without  doing  an  outrage  to  his  nature,  without  con- 
flicting with  his  dearest  desires;  if  he  does  renounce 
it  he  is  in  most  cases  urged  thereto  by  fear,  either  the 
fear  inspired  by  a  master  whom  one  obeys  with 
resignation  or  with  sorrow,  or  the  fear  of  ultimate 
suffering  out  of  all  proportion  to  the  pleasure 
actually  experienced. 

We  must  therefore  discover  everything  that  is 
likely  to  procure  for  us  the  greatest  joy  that  we  can 
experience.  In  the  hope  of  obtaining  greater  happi- 
ness, wre  renounce  certain  innate  or  acquired  tend- 
encies; but  this  greater  happiness  must  be  definite  in 
order  to  exercise  a  greater  attraction ;  it  must  really 
be  the  greatest  possible  for  the  normal  being,  in 
order  that  in  his  search  the  individual  may  have 


148  THE   MORAL   INDIVIDUAL. 

the  assurance  that  nearly  all  his  fellows  recognise 
the  practical  value  of  his  objective  maxims,  approve 
of  him,  encourage  him,  and  will  help  him  if  required, 
and  in  case  of  need  and  under  similar  circumstances 
\vill  act  in  a  similar  manner. 

Moral  action  therefore  depends  on  the  establish- 
ment of  a  hierarchy  of  joys  in  conformity  with  the 
tendencies  of  human  nature.  But  we  may  experience 
pleasure  in  the  accomplishment  of  habitual  acts, 
which  primitively  have  been  accomplished  under 
constraint,  and  then  with  habit  have  become  the 
substance  of  real  needs;  so  that  a  tendency  to 
perform  these  acts  is  gradually  formed,  and  becomes 
stronger  and  stronger;  so  that  eventually  the  sub- 
ject would  experience  pain  in  not  being  able  to 
satisfy  this  tendency,  and  would  experience  pleasure 
in  satisfying  it. 

A  fortiori,  there  is  a  great  number  of  pleasures 
resulting  from  the  habit  which  has  arisen  in  time 
past  of  accomplishing  acts  which  were  agreeable 
from  the  outset.  The  consequence  of  this  habit 
has  been  the  excessive  development  of  the  tendency 
primitively  satisfied,  which  has  very  soon  checked  or 
prevented  the  development  of  more  elevated  tend- 
encies that  might  have  procured  greater  pleasures. 
So  that  the  latter  pleasures  only  being  experienced 
feebly,  or  not  at  all,  either  appear  to  be  of  an  inferior 
order,  or  are  incapable  of  becoming  the  object  of  a 
voluntary  choice. 

These  are  the  pleasures  of  which  M.  Brunschvicg1 
speaks,  when  he  justly  observes  that  "  they  demand 
no  effort  or  initiative;  it  is  sufficient  for  us  to 
abandon  ourselves  to  the  agreeable  impression  which 

1  "  L'ordre  des  joies"  in  Momle  Sociale,  p.  217. 


JOY.  I49 

comes  to  us  from  without.  Such  is  the  habit  of  the 
idle  child,  which  can  do  nothing  but  play.  ...  It  is 
the  imperious  need  of  renewing  the  acts  which  were 
formerly  the  source  of  pleasure,  and  which  no  longer 
procure  that  pleasure,  of  avoiding  every  effort,  of 
allowing  oneself  to  live  in  the  repetition  of  easy  and 
uniform  acts  wrhich  are  of  but  little  value  but  which 
have  cost  nothing." 

We  readily  see  that  the  animal  is  in  general  con- 
tent with  such  pleasure;  the  predominance  of  its 
instinctive  over  its  intellectual  activity,  of  auto- 
matism over  repetition  and  invention,  makes  this 
almost  inevitable.  It  always  experiences  pleasure 
in  play,  perhaps  because  there  is  in  animal  activity 
something  akin  to  human  activity  properly  so 
called.  In  play  it  tries  to  vary  its  pleasures,  and 
it  costs  it  no  effort  to  attain  a  new  type  of  pleasure. 
The  search  for  the  line  of  minimum  resistance  is  not 
very  apparent  here,  to  say  the  least  of  it ;  but  clearer 
is  its  desire  of  disclosing  its  power  and  of  expending 
it  in  pure  waste  without  seeking  the  satisfaction  of 
its  material  needs,  except  in  certain  cases,  which 
are  frequent  enough  it  is  true,  in  which  the  play 
has  as  its  object  the  gratification  of  the  sexual 
instinct. 

In  the  same  way  the  child  often  devotes  itself  to 
work  that  is  painful,  considering  his  strength  and 
years,  to  assure  himself  of  that  pleasure  which  is 
especially  derived  from  the  sentiment  of  a  difficulty 
overcome.  This  sentiment  has  been  of  great  import- 
ance in  the  intellectual  and  practical  evolution  of 
man;  so  much  so  that  we  may  see  in  it,  as  it  were, 
one  of  the  constituent  emotions  of  the  aesthetic 
pleasure.  Besides,  are  not  the  pleasure  of  play  and 


150  THE    MORAL   INDIVIDUAL. 

the  aesthetic  sentiment  closely  united,  especially  in 
the  origin  of  civilisation,  to  the  first  stage  of  the 
uninterrupted  development  of  an  intellect  becoming 
more  and  more  reasonable,  and  of  an  activity  be- 
coming more  and  more  reflective,  intentional,  and 
voluntary  ? l 

71.  Risk  and  Exercise. 

We  must  therefore  make  a  detailed  study  of  the 
pleasure  which  is  produced  by  pursuit  and  conflict, 
a  pleasure  which  gives  rise  to  the  love  of  risk 
that  plays  such  an  important  part  in  Guyau's 
moral  theory.  The  human  pleasure  of  search  con- 
trasts with  the  animal  misoneism;  in  our  curiosity 
there  is  more  than  a  desire  to  know  how  to  respond 
in  an  effective  manner  to  our  numerous  needs;  there 
is  the  satisfaction  of  responding  to  a  tendency  natural 
to  man,  a  tendency  to  incessant  progress  triumphing 
over  blind  resistance.  The  child  likes  obstacles,  he 
creates  them  for  himself,  so  as  to  have  the  pleasure 
of  surmounting  them.  Can  we  forget  this  valuable 
indication  of  an  order  of  pleasures  superior  to  the 
restful  pleasures  which  made  such  an  impression  on 
Epicurus  ? 

"  Once  the  fingers  are  supple,"  says  M.  Brunsch- 
vicg,  "as  if  they  were  penetrated  by  the  mechanism  of 
playing,  once  the  difficulties  of  the  craft  are  over- 
come, then  the  pianist  is  able  to  set  himself  free  to 
attend  to  what  affects  the  mind  in  playing  music, 
— the  intellect  and  feeling.  Instead  of  narrowing 

1  Chamberlain,  op.  cif.,  pp.  10-27;  James,  op.  cit.,  ii.  p.  427; 
Ribot,  op.  cit.,  p.  198  and  pp.  329  et  seq.  ;  Guyau,  Education  and 
Heredity,  p.  164. — TR. 


RISK   AND    EXERCISE. 

little  by  little  the  circle  of  activity,  habit  allows  the 
mind,  assured  of  the  docility  of  the  organism,  to  do 
its  own  \vork  and  to  develop  regularly;  and  the 
more  it  understands  the  more  it  can  understand." 

By  the  side  of  these  intellectual  pleasures,  which 
may  be  renewed  and  widened  in  proportion  as  the 
sphere  of  the  activity  is  renewed  and  widened,  are 
the  social  pleasures  which  also  widen  the  field  of 
difficulties  to  be  overcome,  the  sphere  of  pleasures 
that  a  reasonable  being  can  procure  for  himself.  It 
is  therefore  not  a  restricted,  humble,  and  mean  life — 
that  kind  of  stupor  which  the  Epicureans  called 
apathy — which  suits  man's  nature;  it  is  the  widest 
possible  life,  the  boundaries  of  which  the  scientific, 
aesthetic,  and  social  activity  is  incessantly  moving 
farther  and  farther  back,  surrounding  it  with  mov- 
ing horizons  which  we  know  must  become  more 
and  more  distant,  to  procure  again  and  again  an 
infinite  number  of  new  pleasures  and  new  joys.  To 
the  question,  What  are  the  inferior  and  what  are  the 
superior  joys  ?  we  can  therefore  answer  without 
hesitation : — the  inferior  joys  are  those  which,  ever 
restricting  the  field  of  human  activity,  create  needs 
from  which  man  cannot  free  himself  to  taste  other 
joys.  Higher  joys  are,  on  the  contrary,  those  which 
never  enslave  man,  which  procure  for  him  ample  and 
fruitful  satisfaction,  and  cause  him  to  live  with  the 
utmost  possible  intensity  in  the  widest  and  most 
varied  environment.  The  idea  of  these  joys  crowns 
our  conception  of  the  moral  ideal  from  the  psycho- 
logical point  of  view. 


152     THE    DETERMINISM    OF   IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

V. 

THE  DETERMINISM  OF  IMMORAL  ACTIONS. 

72.  Crime. 

We  can  now  understand  how  it  so  frequently 
happens  that  men  commit  faults  or  fall  into  crime. 
The  tendencies  to  co-ordinate  are  so  numerous,  the 
sentiments  which  ought  to  predominate  have  so 
little  sensible  attraction,  moral  pleasure  is  so  un- 
common, and  virtue  so  difficult  to  realise,  that  we 
ought  not  to  be  astonished  at  the  moral  poverty  of 
humanity. 

Let  us  then  enter  into  detail  as  to  the  determining 
causes  of  crime  or  offences :  we  shall  see  how  errors  of 
conduct  are  connected  with  the  defects  of  our  physio- 
logical, mental,  or  social  nature,  and  how  unnecessary 
is  the  intervention  of  the  vicious  choice  of  free  will 
to  explain  the  fundamental  or  accidental  mechanism 
of  man. 

The  civil  law  calls  every  infringement  of  its  pre- 
scriptions crime  or  misdemeanour.  Every  infringe- 
ment of  the  moral  law  is  an  offence;  but  while  the 
civil  laws  are  clearly  denned,  the  moral  laws  are  often 
indeterminate.  We  cannot  even  say  that  everything 
that  is  contrary  to  the  collective  consciousness  is  a 
fault,  for  this  varying  opinion  of  the  multitude,  to 
which  those  who  have  a  good  reputation  conform,  is 
not  always  such  as  should  be  respected  or  even  faith- 
fully followed,  since  it  sometimes  issues  in  incon- 
sequences, and  owing  to  its  variations  what  was 
forbidden  yesterday_is  legalised  to-day. 


CRIME.  153 

By  what  mark  then  is  an  offence  to  be  recognised, 
if  we  cannot  always  consider  as  a  moral  failure  what 
is  a  breach  of  the  prescriptions  of  the  collective 
conscience,  whether  these  prescriptions  are  always 
formulated  in  the  form  of  laws,  or  remain  without 
formula  although  still  authoritative  ? 

Most  of  the  actions  which  we  regard  as  vicious 
or  defective  are  only  considered  as  such  because  they 
shock  customs,  prejudices,  ideas  accepted  without 
criticism,  and  the  sentiments  instilled  into  the  multi- 
tude by  education,  tradition,  or  imitation.  In  most 
cases,  that  which  is  considered  as  obligatory  takes 
its  necessity  from  the  custom  which  transforms  into 
rigorous  duties  transitory  and  often  equivocal  rules 
of  conduct.  Since  the  duty  is  not  easy  to  determine, 
the  fault  is  also  difficult  to  define.  So  far,  we  have 
always  reasoned  on  the  hypothesis  of  a  moral 
necessity  to  act  according  to  human  nature  both 
psychological  and  sociological,  and  to  give  in  con- 
sequence a  rational  continuation  to  the  natural  de- 
velopment of  our  being — granting  that  it  is  impos- 
sible to  adopt  a  line  of  conduct  which  does  not 
take  into  account  the  requirements  of  human 
nature. 

Fault  may  therefore  be  defined  in  a  very  general 
manner  as  every  action  contrary  to  our  nature  and 
to  social  evolution.  Vice  is  therefore  the  habit  of 
realising  acts  which  are  related  to  a  conduct  to 
which  the  psycho-sociological  study  of  man  can  give 
no  sanction.  But  these  ideas  are  in  both  cases  still 
too  vague. 

Conduct  must  be  systematic.  When  we  speak 
of  a  line  of  conduct,  we  are  as  a  rule  expressing 
by  means  of  a  metaphor  the  bond  which  exists 


154     THE   DETERMINISM    OF   IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

between  the  different  stages  of  an  activity  as 
methodic  as  the  moral  activity  should  be.  Given 
that  moral  action  is  a  voluntary  act,  or  the  habitual 
reproduction  of  a  voluntary  act,  and  that  every  act 
of  this  nature  is  only  such  by  reason  of  the  inter- 
vention of  the  character  in  deliberation  and  choice, 
and  that  it  therefore  flows  from  the  agent's  per- 
sonality, one  and  identical  with  itself,  does  it  not 
follow  that  conduct  ought  to  be  one  and  identical 
with  itself,  like  the  ego,  whose  unity  does  not  prevent 
complexity,  and  whose  identity  does  not  prevent 
development  ?  It  is  the  most  essential  characteristic 
tendencies  which  remain  identical  in  the  agent,  and 
it  is  the  manifestations  of  these  tendencies  which 
remain  identical  in  the  conduct.  But  it  is  impossible 
for  contradictory  acts  to  be  accomplished  at  the 
same  moment,  and  at  two  different  moments  the 
acts  accomplished  cannot  show  by  their  radical 
opposition  that  they  do  not  form  part  of  the  same 
future. 

Conduct,  however,  may  be,  as  we  have  seen,  at 
once  systematically  and  profoundly  vicious.  The  man 
who  persists  in  pursuing  his  evil  courses  presents 
neither  mental  instability  nor  anything  abnormal 
from  the  psychological  point  of  view.  The  mark 
of  his  bad  conduct  will  therefore  no  longer  be  a 
fault  of  intrinsic  systematisation,  but  an  incurable 
discord  with  the  state  of  society  in  which  he  lives. 
No  doubt  it  may  happen  that  a  man  of  the  highest 
moral  worth,  a  Socrates,  for  example,  may  find  him- 
self out  of  harmony  with  the  social  system  of  his 
time;  but  the  discord  is  but  transitory,  and  it  is 
bound  to  disappear  with  the  improvement  of  an 
environment  which  at  first  is  unsympathetic,  and 


CRIME   AND   THE    CRIMINAL.  155 

then,  little  by  little,  places  itself  in  harmony  with 
the  conduct  of  the  virtuous  man.  Even  if  harmony 
is  not  always  established,  at  any  rate  it  can  always 
be  established ;  and  the  sociologist  who  knows 
the  determinism  of  social  facts,  who  can  foresee, 
as  far  as  one  ever  can  foresee,  the  course  of  events, 
may  assert  that  conduct  is  good  when  it  can  be 
reconciled  with  one  of  the  possible  social  systems 
in  the  near  future  or  in  a  future  which  at  the  present 
moment  is  in  the  way  of  realisation. 

Conduct  is  therefore  reprehensible,  because  it  is 
either  intrinsically  unsystematic,  contradictory,  or  un- 
co-ordinated,  now  or  in  its  future,  or  because  it  is  in 
contradiction  with  the  psychological  and  sociological 
laws  of  nature  and  of  the  future.  Because  it  is  such, 
we  may  assert  with  the  utmost  confidence  that  it 
deprives  the  agent  of  a  lasting  happiness,  and  of  that 
moral  joy  wrhich,  as  we  have  defined  it,  can  never 
destroy  the  aptitude  for  higher  joys. 

We  shall  now  go  into  detail,  and  endeavour  to 
discover  the  causes  of  the  immorality  which  is  re- 
vealed by  offences. 


73.  Crime  and  the  Criminal.1 

Shall  we  class  faults  according  to  their  gravity 
from  the  legal,  from  the  psychological,  or  from 
the  sociological  point  of  view  ?  For  these  three 
points  of  viewr  are  different.  The  fault  in  the  eyes 
of  the  legislator  and  the  judge  is  grave  or  light, 
according  as  it  more  or  less  chills  the  social  con- 
science— that  is  to  say,  as  long  as  it  conceals  a 

1  Gallon's  Human  Faculty,  p.  61. 


156     THE    DETERMINISM    OF   IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

will  in  more  or  less  marked  opposition  to  the  collec- 
tive sentiment,  tradition,  morals,  and  to  the  spirit 
of  the  law.  But  the  consideration  of  these  senti- 
ments, of  these  traditions,  and  of  this  spirit  partakes 
of  an  eminently  conservative  tendency;  this  is  be- 
cause the  care  of  preserving  ancient  customs  was 
predominant  among  the  Jews;  and  at  Athens,  for 
instance,  they  compelled  Socrates  to  drink  hemlock 
and  stoned  the  reformers,  although  their  acts  may 
have  hardly  been  considered  serious  from  the  moral 
point  of  view. 

An  offence  in  the  eyes  of  the  sociologist  is  only 
serious  when,  as  we  have  seen,  it  risks  the  destruction 
of  the  social  equilibrium  and  the  continuity  of  the 
collective  future ;  in  the  eyes  of  the  psychologist  it 
is  only  serious  wrhen  it  is  injurious  to  the  mental 
well-being,  the  stability  of  the  mental  life,  and  the 
regularity  of  the  psychic  evolution.  The  moralist, 
who  has  the  interests  of  both  the  psychologist  and 
of  the  sociologist  to  bear  in  mind,  cannot  make 
an  abstraction  of  the  person,  and  if  he  cannot 
abstain  from  considering  the  individual  in  the 
social  environment,  he  cannot  do  otherwise  than 
see  the  act  in  the  agent,  and  conceive  of  the  action, 
on  one  side  with  its  social  effects,  and  on  the 
other  with  its  psychological  and  sociological 
factors. 

That  is  why,  instead  of  classing  crimes  and  mis- 
demeanours according  to  the  gravity  attached  to 
them  by  the  law,  or  even  according  to  the  social 
institutions  injured  by  the  delinquent,  contemporary 
criminologists  endeavour  to  make  a  classification  of 
criminals.  Lombroso1  makes  of  the  criminal  an 

1  Havelock  Ellis,  op.  «'/.,  p.  36,— TR. 


CRIME   AND   THE   CRIMINAL.  157 

abstract  being,  analogous,  as  Ferri  remarks,  to 
Quetelet's  " average  man."  His  delinquent  is  a 
synthesis  of  the  vices,  faults,  aptitudes,  deformi- 
ties or  anomalies  observable  in  the  different  types, 
different  enough  for  us  to  oppose  to  the  illus- 
trious Italian  anthropologist  the  work  of  Gall, 
Fregier,  Ferrus,  Despine,  Maudsley,  Morselli,  Sergi, 
and  Ferri,  among  the  numerous  band  who  have  tried 
to  establish  a  classification  of  criminals.  Gall  dis- 
tinguished between  the  impulsive  and  the  instinctive, 
originally  vicious;  Fregier,  in  his  reflections  on  the 
memoirs  of  Vidocq,  separated  the  professional  from 
the  chance  or  necessitous  thief.  E.  Ferri  recalls 
the  enumeration  made  by  Du  Camp  (without  any 
scientific  basis,  let  me  remark),  of  the  many  varieties 
of  the  low-class  thief  and  the  swell  mob.  Ferrus 
classed  delinquents  according  to  their  intellectual 
development:  i,  those  who  have  moderate  intelli- 
gence and  bad  congenital  tendencies;  2,  those  who 
have  ordinary  intelligence,  but  are  only  addicted  to 
debauchery,  vagabondage,  and  crime  from  mental 
inertia  and  weakness  of  the  moral  sense;  3,  those 
who  from  defective  cerebral  organisation  are  unfit 
for  any  serious  occupation,  whether  they  are  per- 
verse, energetic,  or  intelligent,  doing  wrong  in  a 
systematic  manner,  or  those  who  are  vicious, 
obtuse,  and  incapable  of  resisting  evil  impulses,  or 
finally,  those  who  are  criminal  without  having  any 
notion  of  the  nature  of  their  acts.  Despine  drew  a 
distinction  between  criminals  cool,  impulsive,  morally 
abnormal,  with  or  even  without  mental  alienation. 
Huret,  who  has  made  a  special  study  of  convicts, 
divides  them  into  three  groups :  the  non-vicious,  who 
have  acted  under  the  influence  of  a  violent  and 


158     THE    DETERMINISM   OF   IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

sudden  emotion;  the  rebels,  who  are  masters  of  the 
art  of  crime;  and  those  who  are  dull  and  brutalised, 
and  who  are  sometimes  dominated  by  their  more 
fundamentally  vicious  companions. 

Ferri  has  endeavoured  to  show  the  existence  of 
two  great  classes  of  criminals — the  criminal  born, 
the  incorrigible,  in  whom  crime  is  a  habit,  and  the 
occasional  delinquents,  in  whom  the  anatomical  and 
psycho  -  pathological  characteristics  of  Lombroso's 
criminal  are  more  or  less  absent.  In  1880  he  pro- 
posed five  categories  connected  with  the  two  prin- 
cipal types — the  insane ;  the  criminal  born ;  habitual, 
occasional,  and  impulsive  delinquents. 

M.  le  Bon  has  also  established  the  existence  of 
two  fundamental  classes,  that  of  criminals  of  here- 
ditary disposition  (criminal-born,  impulsive,  of 
weak  character,  and  intelligent,  but  deprived  of 
moral  sense),  and  that  of  criminals  in  conse- 
quence of  an  acquired  lesion  of  the  moral  sense 
(through  alcoholism,  general  paralysis,  cerebral 
lesions,  etc.). 

M.  Laccassagne  distinguishes  between  criminals 
by  sentiment  or  by  instinct,  vicious  from  heredity  or 
acquired  habit,  occasional  or  impulsive  delinquents, 
and  insane  delinquents. 

It  is  useless  to  multiply  the  analyses  of  so  many 
classifications  made  from  so  many  different  points  of 
view,  among  wrhich  those  of  Maudsley,  Garofalo, 
Sergi,  Yvernes,  are  distinguished  by  etiological, 
psychological,  or  sociological  considerations  which, 
taken  separately,  have  an  importance  of  their 
own.1 

1   Vide  a  complete  and  impartial  exposition  of  these  theories  in  Ferri, 
Sociologia  criminals  (4th  edition,  1900). 


UNIVERSITY    ) 

CLASSIFICATIOtfVAND  DESCRIPTIVE  SUMMAKY.    159 

74.  Classification  and  Descriptive  Summary. 

From  their  comparative  examination,  says  E. 
Ferri,  it  follows :  first,  that  we  must  give  up  the  old 
conception  of  the  criminal  of  uniform  type ;  second, 
that  the  distinction  between  the  occasional  criminal 
who  may  be  cured,  and  the  delinquent  by  instinct 
and  by  hereditary  tendency  who  is  incorrigible,  is 
generally  accepted,  as  well  as  the  subdivision  into 
occasional  and  impulsive  delinquents,  the  criminal- 
born  and  the  insane  criminal. 

It  therefore  seems  that  the  classification  which  is 
based  on  the  etiology  of  misdemeanour  and  crime 
should  serve  as  a  basis  for  the  description  of  the 
essential  characters  of  each  criminal  type,  whether 
those  characters  are  psychological  or  sociological. 

The  criminal  born  is  presented  as  savage,  brutal, 
and  knavish,  incapable  of  distinguishing  theft  or 
crime  from  any  kind  of  honest  activity;  he  is  a 
delinquent,  according  to  Fregier,1  just  as  others  are 
good  workers,  dreading  pain  more  than  he  is  affected 
by  it  when  it  is  inflicted,  for  he  considers  a  prison 
as  an  asylum  where  his  subsistence  is  assured  in 
idleness.  He  is  always  an  impenitent  recidivist. 

The  habitual  criminal  is  a  weak  character,  who 
has  often  experienced  a  morbid  impulse,  and  has 
been  encouraged  to  the  repetition  of  crime,  sometimes 
by  the  impunity  that  is  assured  to  acts  but  slightly 
criminal,  and  sometimes  owing  to  bad  company. 
Imprisonment,  life  in  common  with  beings  without 
morality,  has  been  fatal  to  his  moral  sense,  and  has 
perverted  or  completely  destroyed  it.  Imprisonment 
in  a  cell  has  stupefied  him,  alcoholism  has  brutalised 

1  Les  classes  dangereuses,  p.  175,  Brussels,  1840. 


l6o     THE   DETERMINISM   OF   IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

him,  and  the  fact  that  society  will  have  none  of  him 
from  the  time  of  his  first  lapses,  has  thrown  him 
into  idleness  and  exposed  him  to  every  kind  of 
temptation.1  His  characteristics  are  precocity  and 
a  tendency  to  the  repetition  of  crime.  This  type  is 
that  of  many  young  fellows,  morally  abandoned  by 
their  families  or  brought  up  in  the  midst  of  vice,  and 
it  is  men  like  him,  as  the  numbers  of  this  class 
increase,  who  make  juvenile  criminality  more  and 
more  a  subject  of  anxiety. 


75.  The  Criminal  by  Accident? 

The  criminal  by  accident  and  the  criminal  by 
impulse  are  distinct  from  the  criminal-born  and  from 
the  delinquent  in  whom  crime  has  become  habitual 
from  a  kind  of  impotence  to  resist  certain  impulses, 
the  psycho-pathological  nature  of  which  is  evident. 

The  former  experience  no  repugnance  in  doing 
wrong ;  the  latter  do  it  sometimes  in  spite  of  their 
repugnance,  or  at  any  rate  in  spite  of  their  habitual 
tendency  to  abstain  from  offensive  and  criminal 
actions.  They  usually  present,  under  most  circum- 
stances in  their  lives,  the  character  of  normal  beings 
of  variable  intelligence.  However,  when  we  examine 
them  closely,  we  quickly  discover  in  them  a  weak 
will,  a  mental  instability,  sometimes  generalised  and 
sometimes  purely  intellectual  or  emotional ;  and  it  is 
precisely  this  lack  of  strength  of  character  which 
is  the  cause  of  their  not  resisting  the  "  psychological 
storm,"  as  Ferri  calls  the  disorder  of  mind  caused  by 
a  strong  passion,  by  sudden  impulse  due  to  instinctive 

1  E.  Ferri,  op.  cit.,  p.  228. 

-  Lombroso,  The  Female  Offender^  chap.  xiii.  —  TR, 


THE    CRIMINAL    BY   ACCIDENT.  l6l 

sympathy,  to  imitation  or  to  moral  contagion,  or 
finally  to  the  generally  subconscious  obsession  which 
slowly  brings  on  the  inevitable  crisis  in  which  some- 
times both  the  honour  and  the  morality  of  an  indi- 
vidual are  wrecked.  The  impulsive  are  sometimes 
recognised  by  their  continual  exaltation,  their  irrita- 
bility, and  their  promptitude  to  re-act  violently  even 
under  slight  stimuli ;  and  at  other  times  again  they 
are  merely  extravagant  in  their  sentiments,  manners, 
language,  re-actions,  and  tendencies  on  some  single 
point.  They  are  shrewd  as  far  as  all  other  questions 
are  concerned ;  they  show  lack  of  judgment,  lack  of 
tact,  and  lack  of  restraint,  whenever  the  object 
of  their  passion  is  the  cause  of  it;  they  are  ready 
to  burst  into  a  fury  if  we  "touch  the  tender 
spot." 

The  impulsive  and  the  accidental  delinquent  may 
frequently  fall  into  the  repetition  of  crime,  contrary  to 
the  opinion  of  certain  criminologists,  who  are  parti- 
cularly anxious  to  place  the  two  principal  classes  of 
criminals  in  contrast  with  respect  to  this  point. 
Now  nothing  guarantees  them  against  the  involun- 
tary return  to  fresh  offences,  but  after  each  lapse  they 
again  show  repentance,  a  sincere  regret  for  the  evil 
action  of  which  their  weakness  is  the  cause,  and 
which  they  voluntarily  attribute  to  fate,  to  a  force 
greater  than  themselves,  so  conscious  are  they  of 
not  having  acted  in  accordance  with  the  fundamental 
tendencies  of  their  being.  There  is  therefore  every 
reason  to  distinguish  them  clearly  from  the  brutes 
whose  moral  sense  has  been  obliterated  by  heredity 
or  bad  habit.  But  should  not  both  of  these  classes 
be  brought  into  closer  relation  to  the  case  of  the 
insane  criminal  ? 

ii 


l62      THE    DETERMINISM    OF    IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

76.  Insane  Criminals.1 

Do  not  these  form  a  very  complex  class,  from 
which  might  be  established  numerous  subdivisions 
corresponding  to  every  possible  type  of  immorality? 
Should  we  not  find  in  this  class  the  analogue  not 
only  of  the  born  criminal,  of  the  criminal  by 
habit,  of  the  impulsive  and  of  the  accidental  delin- 
quent, but  also  of  every  being  who  has  vices  less 
odious  than  those  of  the  criminal,  or  who  simply 
and  accidentally  commits  faults  and  immoral 
actions  ?  Are  not  all  the  facts  of  immorality  cases 
of  more  or  less  attenuated  "  moral  insanity  "  ? 

By  the  words  "  moral  insanity "  we  generally 
understand  a  particular  kind  of  mental  infirmity, 
which  especially  consists  in  a  defect  or  a  disturbance 
of  the  moral  sense,  without  the  intellectual  functions 
being  necessarily  affected;  that  is  why  Prichard2 
called  it  moral  insanity  with  much  more  accuracy 
than  Verga,  who  called  it  reasoning  mania.  For  it 
is  not  so  much  a  question  of  the  preservation  of  the 
power  of  reasoning,  which  in  certain  cases  may  be 
weakened,  as  of  the  weakness  of  the  powrer  of  acting 
in  a  rational,  systematic  manner.  Certain  Anglo- 
American  alienists  have  preferred  to  the  names  of 
moral  insanity,  moral  imbecility,  or  reasoning  mania, 
that  of  affective  insanity,  the  term  which  is  used 
by  Savage  and  Hughes.3 

1  Despine,    Psychologic  Naturelle,  ii.    pp.    169  et  seq.;    Maudsley, 
Pathology  of  Mind ;  Art.    "  Criminal   Anthropology,"   by   H.    Ellis, 
Dictionary  of  Psychological  Medicine ;  Guyau,  Education  et  Heredite, 
p.  94;  Lombroso,  The  Female  Offender ;  chaps,  xvii.,  xviii.;  Maudsley, 
Body  and  Mind,  pp.  62  et  seq. — TR. 

2  Cf.   Ribot,  op.  cit.,  pp.  300,  301.— TR. 

3  Maudsley,  Responsibility  in  Mental  Disease,  chap,  v.,  Part  I.— TR. 


IMMORALITY    OF   THE    IMBECILE.  163 

As  a  matter  of  fact,  moral  madness  seems  to  be  no- 
thing but  a  morbid  condition  corresponding  to  the 
numerous  relations  of  conduct  with  the  varied  forms 
of  mental  alienation.  There  are  no  doubt  especially 
interesting  cases  in  which  with  a  remarkable  activity 
of  the  intellectual  functions  by  a  curious  anomaly 
is  combined  exceptionally  vicious  conduct ;  but  how 
can  we  establish  a  distinction  between  these  cases  and 
those  in  which  we  see  progressively  an  ineptitude  to 
moral  life,  associating  itself  with  lower  and  lower  de- 
grees of  intellectual  life  ?  Is  there  not  a  continuous 
series  of  which  pure  moral  imbecility  is  the  last  term 
while  ordinary  imbecility  or  idiocy  is  the  first  term  ? 
Can  we  state  an  essential  difference  between  the  im- 
morality of  the  idiot  and  that  of  the  "  moral  madman  "  ? 

77.  Immorality  of  the  Imbecile.1 

To  the  brutality,  the  knavery,  and  the  idleness 
of  the  born  criminal  correspond  the  tendencies  of 
certain  imbeciles  who  are,  as  M.  Sollier2  points  out, 
wicked,  idle,  misguided,  anti-social  beings,  and,  as 
M.  Legrain3  puts  it,  sly  and  vicious  creatures,  im- 
pelled by  a  kind  of  destructive  instinct  (although 
certain  of  them  may  be  gentle,  kind,  and  bene- 
volent).4 Now  ought  we  not  to  consider  idiocy  and 
imbecility  as  the  inferior  degrees  of  that  degeneration 

1  Guyau,  Edttcation  et  Heredite,  p.  94  ;  Maudsley,  Body  and  Mind, 
pp.  65  et  seq.,  and  Responsibility  in  Mental  Disease,  pp.  179  et  seq. — TR. 

2  Psychologic  de  F  Idiot  et  de  I' Imbecile.     Alcan,  1891. 

3  Du  Delire  chez  les  Deg'eneres. 

4  D.  Francois  .   .   .  imbecile  aged  forty,  watches  with  the  greatest 
care  over  his  idiot  brother  and  sister ;  he  lavishes  on  them  the  most 
assiduous   attention,    and   shows   exemplary   kindness    to    everybody. 
(Observation  taken  in  the  asylum,  Alencon.) 


164     THE    DETERMINISM    OF    IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

which  causes  certain  insane  people  to  have  a  moral 
future  analogous  to  the  abnormal  development  of 
the  hardened  criminal,  persisting  in  immorality  in 
spite  of  even  the  most  severe  pain  ?  Between  the 
imbecile  and  the  "  moral  madman  "  there  is  only  a 
difference  of  degree,  no  difference  in  nature.  The 
former  is  degenerate,  because  the  check  to  his 
development  that  he  has  undergone  has  deprived 
him  of  certain  intellectual  faculties,  and  at  the  same 
time  of  higher  affections  and  of  every  normal  moral 
sentiment.  The  latter  is  a  degenerate  in  whom  the 
check  of  development  has  only  affected  a  smaller 
number  of  mental  functions,  so  that  higher  modes 
of  the  intelligence  have  appeared,  but  the  correspond- 
ing modes  of  sensibility  and  activity  have  been 
unable  to  effect  their  normal  evolution.  M.  Magnan 
considers  the  imbecile  as  "  an  idiot,  in  whom  certain 
centres  of  the  anterior  cerebral  region  have  been  left 
unaffected/'  and  who  is  therefore  "capable  of  ideo- 
motor  determinations,"  capable  of  "  penetrating  into 
the  domain  of  intellectual  control,"  and  of  raising  him- 
self sometimes  so  far  as  to  possess  curious  aptitudes, 
until  he  becomes  what  has  been  called  a  "partial 
genius."i 

If  he  only  lacks  moral  aptitudes  he  no  longer  pre- 
sents the  characters  of  ordinary  imbecility.  There  is 
nothing  in  him  now  but  "  moral  imbecility."  Need 
his  immorality  be  explained  otherwise  than  in  those 
cases  in  which  the  degree  of  intelligence  is  much  less  ? 

78.  Intelligent  Degenerates. 

The  intelligent  degenerate,  like  the  habitual 
criminal,  is  precocious  in  vice;  he  does  wrong  for 

1  Magnan,  Lemons  cliniques  stir  les  Maladies  mentales.     Alcan,  1897. 


INTELLIGENT   DEGENERATES.  165 

wrong's  sake  with  a  kind  of  morbid  enjoyment.  He 
is  proud  of  his  increasing  perversity,  and  he  does  not 
hide  his  immorality  under  a  bushel.  Prompt  to 
imitate  bad  actions,  he  contracts  from  an  early  age 
vicious  habits,  which  will  be  so  many  centres  of 
attraction  for  further  depraved  habits. 

B.  R.1  is  eighteen  years  of  age:  he  belongs  to 
an  unbalanced  family;  his  father  is  alcoholic,  his 
mother  is  a  prostitute;  his  eldest  brother,  at  present 
a  deserter,  has  been  sent  to  a  disciplinary  regiment; 
another  brother  is  confined  in  a  house  of  correction. 
From  the  age  of  nine  he  tried  to  rival  his  mother's 
immorality.  From  this  resulted  a  morbid  tendency 
to  the  satisfaction  of  the  sexual  instinct,  which 
impelled  this  youth  at  the  age  of  thirteen  to  various 
brutal  assaults  upon  women  and  girls.  At  present 
B.  R.  .  .  .  has  no  pleasure  left  to  him  except  that 
which  he  experiences  in  relating  his  deeds  of  sexual 
perversity;  he  shows  no  remorse,  he  has  no  con- 
sciousness of  the  repulsion  that  is  inspired  by  his 
assaults,  and  by  the  whole  of  his  evil  past.  On  the 
28th  May  1900,  he  succeeds  in  making  his  escape 
for  several  hours,  and  commits  new  crimes.  On 
the  22nd  April  he  walks  in  front  of  a  group  kof  women 
and  girls  whose  attention  he  wishes  to  attract.  He 
does  not  succeed,  and  ascertains  with  disgust  that  a 
megalo-maniac  has  much  more  chance  of  attracting 
the  attention  of  this  group  of  women.  He  then  pro- 
ceeds to  shout,  gesticulate,  jump,  and  dance  about  on 
the  ground;  then  being  seized  as  it  were  with  a  fit 

1  The  observations  on  this  case  of  moral  insanity  are  due  to  the 
kindness  of  Dr.  Tourniac,  Medical  Superintendent  of  the  asylum  at 
Auxerre,  who  has  been  good  enough  to  allow  me  to  share  in  his 
researches  on  mental  alienation. 


l66     THE   DETERMINISM    OF   IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

of  fury,  he  strikes  his  keepers,  .breaks  the  panels  of 
the  doors,  and  then  calms  down  suddenly  when  he 
finds  out  that  at  last  they  have  noticed  him.  Several 
times,  and  here  again  simply  to  attract  attention, 
he  pretended  to  commit  suicide,  and  at  last  one 
day,  the  victim  of  his  own  antics,  he  really  hanged 
himself. 

This,  then,  is  the  case  of  a  degenerate  in  whom  the 
sexual  instinct,  combined  with  vanity,  played  the 
principal  role.  He  experienced  neither  affection,  nor 
modesty,  nor  restraint,  nor  religious  feeling,  nor  the 
aesthetic  sense.  He  was  a  knave,  a  hypocrite, 
revengeful,  incapable  of  feeling  regret  or  remorse, 
insensible  to  reproaches,  to  contempt,  or  to  affec- 
tionate words.  He  was  for  a  considerable  period  in 
a  house  of  correction,  and  his  fundamental  worthless- 
ness  was  increased  by  his  contact  with  numerous 
little  good-for-nothings,  to  whom  he  admiringly 
related  his  prowess.  He  especially  frequented  the 
society  of  adults,  so  that  he  might  learn  from  them 
as  much  wickedness  as  possible.  Now  this  is  a 
monster  from  the  moral  point  of  view,  but  a  monster 
with  an  intellectual  side.  Why  is  he  so  profoundly 
vicious,  if  not  because  his  physical  and  mental  con- 
stitution, his  cerebral  capacity,  have  not  allowed  the 
development  of  those  affectionate,  aesthetic,  and 
social  sentiments,  without  which,  as  we  have  seen, 
morality  cannot  exist  ?  If  he  may  serve  as  an 
example  of  the  delinquent  from  vicious  habit,  do  we 
not  see  that  criminals  of  this  type  may,  at  any 
rate  for  the  most  part,  be  fairly  compared  to  the 
insane,  whether  criminals  or  not,  whom  congenital 
or  acquired  degeneration  has  shut  up  in  our 
asylums  ? 


THE    UNBALANCED.  167 

79.  The  Unbalanced. 

There  is  among  the  criminals  of  whom  we  speak  a 
considerable  number  of  people  who  show  signs  of 
elevated  sentiments,  and  in  whom  it  would  seem 
there  is  no  defect  in  that  mental  development  which 
permits  us  to  judge  sanely  and  to  feel  keenly  the 
immorality  of  criminal  actions.  These  are  compar- 
able to  other  insane  cases  of  which  Fr.  .  .  .  may 
furnish  a  type. 

Fr.  ...  is  the  eldest  of  a  family  of  eight  children, 
which  does  not  contain  any  other  disequilibrated 
member,  but  of  which  two  or  three  are  of  doubtful 
morality.  He  is  a  well-educated  man  who  has 
received  an  excellent  secondary  education,  and  who 
thoroughly  understands  the  arguments  one  opposes 
to  his  own,  and  who  can  engage  in  discussion  with 
considerable  sagacity,  but  who  obviously  uses  his 
intellectual  aptitudes  to  justify  the  acts  he  commits 
after  they  have  been  committed.  He  abused  the 
confidence  of  a  post-office  employe  to  make  him 
hand  over  letters  addressed  to  two  of  his  brothers 
with  whom  he  had  had  some  disagreement.  He 
wrote  threatening  letters  to  people,  who  were  not 
much  troubled  thereby,  and  who  thought,  not  with- 
out reason  perhaps,  that  they  were  attempts  at 
blackmail.  He  attracted  to  himself  the  attention  of 
the  public  by  foolish  or  criminal  acts  with  the  object 
of  embarrassing  his  family  because  they  had  refused 
him  money.  Fr.  ...  is  therefore,  from  the  practical 
point  of  view,  an  anti-social  being,  a  delinquent  who 
would  probably  not  refrain  from  crime  if  he  had  the 
opportunity.  On  several  occasions  he  has  threatened 
cruel  vengeance  to  his  keepers  if  he  should  ever  get 


l68     THE    DETERMINISM    OF    IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

out  of  the  asylum.  He  is  revengeful  and  spiteful; 
in  fact,  all  his  acts  belie  his  words;  but  as  he  has 
considerable  intelligence,  he  explains  all  his  antics  in 
the  most  astonishing  way;  he  knows  how  to  present 
them  in  the  most  favourable  light,  and  if  he  cannot 
justify  them  completely,  at  any  rate  he  diminishes 
their  importance  in  such  a  way  that  he  thinks  he  is 
entirely  free  from  blame,  and  therefore  experiences 
no  remorse.  Now,  if  wre  look  into  this  closely,  we 
see  that  the  sentiments  he  expounds  so  brilliantly, 
and  with  which  one  would  almost  think  he  was 
saturated,  are  only  skin  deep.  He  is  never  really 
moved,  either  by  suffering  or  by  the  happiness  of 
others;  he  is  incapable  of  a  generous  action  or  of  a 
disinterested  movement.  He  has  an  abstract  con- 
ception of  the  sentiments  of  which  he  speaks,  but  he 
no  longer  experiences  them.  Is  not  this  a  remark- 
able case  of  the  failure  of  the  affective  part  of  a 
being,  much  anterior  to  the  intellectual  failure  which 
no  doubt  will  later  ensue  ? 

And  may  not  this  observation  serve  to  explain  how 
criminals  without  any  apparent  mental  anomaly  are 
scarcely  more  able  than  imbeciles,  or  inferior  de- 
generates, to  re-act  against  their  gross  appetites  and 
their  increasing  tendencies  to  vicious  and  immoral 
activity  ? 

80.  The  Criminal  by  Passion.1 

We  now  pass  on  to  a  class  intermediary  between 
that  of  criminals  from  inveterate,  vicious  habit,  and 

1  Havelock  Ellis,  The  Criminal,  p.  2 ;  Hoffbauer,  Med.  Leg.  relative 
aux  alienes,  1837,  pp.  259-270;  Fere,  Pathology  of  Emotions,  p.  506; 
Ribot,  op.  cit.,  p.  301  ;  Lombioso,  71ie  Female  Offender,  chap.  xv.  ; 
Maudsley,  Responsibility  in  Mental  Disease,  chap.  v. — TR. 


THE   CRIMINAL   BY   PASSION.  l6g 

that  of  occasional  criminals,  that  of  the  criminal  by 
passion,  whether  obsessed  or  not.  We  can  scarcely 
refuse  to  recognise  the  relationship  of  these  young 
evil-doers,  of  these  beings  who  are  so  often 
dangerous,  and  who  suddenly  and  unexpectedly 
commit  the  greatest  crimes,  to  certain  cases  of 
insanity,  of  which  the  girl  PI.  ...  will  exhibit  to  us 
both  the  character  and  the  mode  of  action. 

PL  ...  is  a  girl  of  fifteen,  who  on  the  2Oth  of 
July  1899  voluntarily  set  fire  to  a  rick  of  hay,1  and 
who  on  the  i8th  August  in  the  same  year  tried  to 
suffocate  the  child  of  her  master,  aged  thirteen 
months.  She  did  not  confess  these  crimes  until 
the  26th  August,  having  done  all  she  could  until 
then  to  escape  suspicion.  Since  then  it  seems  she 
has  experienced  no  remorse,  has  shown  no  regret, 
and  when  questioned  on  the  subject  of  her  acts,  she 
speaks  of  them  with  astounding  placidity;  at  most 
she  is  annoyed  because  she  is  questioned  so  often. 
She  has  stated  to  the  magistrate  that  she  was  not  at 
all  affected  when  she  committed  the  second  crime, 
and  witnesses  affirm  that  she  showed  no  emotion 
when  she  was  told  of  its  discovery. 

Now  what  is  most  surprising  is  that  she  had 
never  shown  the  least  sentiment  of  hostility  to  her 
masters,  and  that  she  admitted  she  had  always  been 
well  treated  by  them.  She  asserts  that  she  did 
nothing  from  anger  or  from  a  spirit  of  vengeance, 


1  Pyromania  is  sometimes  found  unassociated  with  other  forms  of 
mental  disorder.  But  it  is  also  found  in  association  with  thievish 
impulses,  suicidal  tendencies,  religious  mania,  and  with  disorders  of 
the  sexual  functions. —  Vide  Maudsley,  Responsibility  in  Mental  Disease, 
pp.  81,  161,  163;  Ribot,  op.  «'/.,  p.  225;  Morselli,  Sttiade,  pp.  123, 
151.— TR. 


170     THE    DETERMINISM    OF    IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

and  it  really  seems  that  never  having  been  re- 
proached, never  having  suffered  the  slightest  annoy- 
ance in  the  house,  she  could  not  have  been  urged  to 
these  crimes  through  any  malicious  feeling. 

But  if  she  felt  no  hatred,  and  if  she  did  not  act 
under  the  influence  of  anger,  at  any  rate  she  was  not 
restrained  by  any  feeling  of  affection,  for  she  shows 
herself  quite  incapable  of  experiencing  such  a  feeling. 
She  does  not  like  animals.  She  experiences  none  of 
the  pleasures  of  children  of  her  own  age,  or  even  of 
younger  children.  She  declares  that  she  has  never 
strangled  birds  or  drowned  cats;  but  if  it  were  done 
in  her  presence  she  would  be  indifferent,  and  to 
everything  she  shows  the  same  indifference.  She 
did  not  want  to  go  to  a  concert :  "  it  would  not  be 
unpleasant,  but  at  the  same  time  would  not  please 
her."  She  would  not  put  herself  out  either  to  see  a 
beautiful  picture  or  to  hear  beautiful  singing. 

This  absence  of  interest  in  most  of  the  objects 
which  attract  the  attention  of  the  normal  child  has 
turned  PL  ...  into  a  naughty  school-girl,  learning 
nothing  and  remembering  nothing  of  the  lessons  she 
received.  She  knows  perfectly  well,  however,  that 
certain  actions  are  dishonest  or  criminal ;  she  under- 
stands that  there  are  crimes  which  are  repugnant  to 
the  conscience  of  most  people.  A  proof  of  this  is, 
that  she  does  not  ignore  the  misconduct  of  her 
mother;  that  she  knowrs  quite  well  why  her  father 
left  his  family  and  went  to  live  away;  and  yet  she 
refuses  to  give  the  least  explanation  on  this  point. 
It  is  not  that  she  disapproved  personally  of  her 
mother's  acts,  but  rather,  that  she  learned  by  experi- 
ence and  since  her  childhood  that  it  was  not  a  thing 
which  ought  to  be  talked  about;  and  in  the  same 


THE   CRIMINAL   BY   PASSION. 

way  she  does  not  wish  to  speak  of  her  own  crimes: 
she  pretends  to  remember  nothing  at  all,  not  even 
the  name  of  her  late  master.1 

The  indifference  in  matters  of  morality  which 
seems  to  us  well  established  in  the  present  case, 
has  permitted  the  sudden  rise  and  development  of 
impulses.  PL  ...  has  many  times  confessed  that 
she  had  no  idea  of  suffocating  the  child  when  cross- 
ing the  threshold  of  the  court,  through  which  she  had 
to  pass  from  the  stable  (where  she  had  been  quietly 
milking  with  her  mistress  and  another  servant),  in 
order  to  reach  the  dwelling,  where  she  was  going  to 
a  small  cistern.  She  went  into  the  room  where 
her  little  victim  was  sleeping  and  placed  the  infant 
between  two  feather-beds;  she  removed  a  pane  of 
glass  which  was  almost  out  of  the  window,  carefully 
opened  the  window,  and  left  it  open  to  encourage 
the  idea  of  the  criminal  being  a  miscreant  from 
without,  an  enemy  of  the  house.  During  the  course 
of  the  day  she  went  to  the  cellar  and  upset  the  butter 
and  the  milk  further  to  confirm  the  notion  (and  in 
this  she  was  quite  successful)  that  the  act  was  that  of 
a  stranger.  The  impulse  was  not  therefore  followed 
by  forgetfulness ;  it  did  not  form  part  of  a  moment 
in  which  the  consciousness  was  less  clear,  in  which 
the  personality  underwent  a  transitory  change,  or  in 
which  was  produced,  as  it  were,  a  fugitive  mental 
alienation.  The  impulse  is  easily  integrated  while 
it  lasted,  and  although  it  seems  inexplicable  when 
we  take  all  the  antecedents  into  account,  it  ex- 
plains a  whole  series  of  consequences:  the  new 
crime,  and  the  period  of  long  dissimulation,  which 
does  not,  however,  seem  to  cause  distress  to  the 

1  Cf.  Havelock  Ellis,  op.  cit.,  pp.  7,  211.— TR. 


172     THE   DETERMINISM   OF   IMMORAL   ACTION. 

young  criminal,  in  spite  of  the  suspicions  which  were 
entertained  by  the  servant,  who  alone  was  wiser  in 
this  respect  than  the  other  people  in  the  house. 
The  incendiary  and  homicidal  impulses  have  on  all 
points  the  same  characteristics.  There  is  no  hysteri- 
form  character,  no  somnambulism,  nothing  but 
mental  instability  and  a  fairly  complete  absence 
of  the  social  sentiments;  the  causes  of  the  crime 
are  therefore  deficient  rather  than  efficient. 

And  so  it  is  with  the  faults  committed  by  most 
degenerates;  such  as,  for  instance,  the  impulsive  who 
strike  their  relations  or  the  friends  of  the  house 
rather  than  strangers  or  enemies.  From  the  moral 
point  of  view  they  are  little  better  than  the  weak- 
minded,  the  imbeciles,  or  idiots,  who  have  no  sys- 
tematic conduct,  who  are  more  or  less  incapable 
of  co-ordinating  their  desires  or  actions;  who  have 
undergone  an  arrested  development,  not  only  in  their 
intellectual  faculties,  but  in  their  sentiments,  tend- 
encies, and  aptitude  to  experience  emotions;  who, 
in  short,  would  be  led  to  automatic  and  instinctive 
rather  than  to  intelligent  and  reflective  activity,  but 
who  have  unfortunately  neither  the  fixed  and  power- 
ful instincts  of  the  animal,  nor  the  still  tenacious 
habits  of  the  insane,  nor  of  those  men  of  the  world 
who  are  really  automata  as  far  as  politeness  and 
good  manners  are  concerned. 

According  to  M.  Dallemagne,  "  given  that  every 
individual  act  of  the  normal  life,  and  therefore  every 
social  manifestation,  affects  directly  or  indirectly  the 
three  great  functions,  the  nutritive,  the  genetic,  and 
the  intellectual,"  crime  is  due  to  the  unsatiated  or 
incompletely  satiated  needs  which  refer  to  these 
great  functions.  "The  unsatisfied  functions  create 


THE    CRIMINAL    BY    PASSION.  173 

in  their  respective  centres  a  tension  which  objectively 
renders  the  consecutive  discharge  more  violent  and 
more  spontaneous,  and  subjectively  gives  rise  to  the 
whole  gamut  of -sensations,  which  range  from  the 
simple  feeling  of  indefinable  uneasiness  to  the  pain 
which  overclouds  and  obscures  the  consciousness." 
This,  in  many  cases,  is  the  explanation  even  of 
morbid  impulses;  but  in  crime  there  is  something 
else  besides  impulses,  something  more  than  the  auto- 
matism of  different  centres;  there  is  a  functional 
incapacity  of  certain  centres,  the  temporary  or  de- 
finitive inhibition  of  certain  functions,  and  the  non- 
co-ordination  of  certain  others — in  short,  mental 
instability,  with  the  resultant  clouding  over  or  pro- 
gressive disappearance  of  the  representations,  tend- 
encies, and  sentiments  which  are  indispensable  to 
mental  and  moral  equilibrium.  Hence  there  is  no 
reasoning  issuing  in  moral  conclusions:  there  is  no 
longer  any  room  except  by  accident  for  subtle  cal- 
culations determined  by  an  affection  or  an  inclination 
of  an  inferior  order. 

The  misdemeanours  of  a  vagabond  life  form  the 
simplest  type  of  the  immoral  effects  of  pathological 
instability.  There  is  no  family  sentiment,  no  love  of 
work,  respect  for  the  law,  for  authority,  for  human 
dignity ;  no  social,  aesthetic,  and  religious  tendencies 
—if  ever  these  different  affective  methods  have  existed 
in  the  mind  of  the  vagabond;  there  is  nothing  but  a 
morbid  love  of  change  of  residence,  and  of  living  on 
the  proceeds  of  chance. 

How  many  bad  habits  and  tendencies  then  spring 
into  being,  which  are  with  difficulty  restrained!  for 
they  meet  with  no  obstacle  of  a  moral  nature,  because 
such  obstacles  either  have  not  been  formed,  or,  if 


174     THE    DETERMINISM    OF    IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

formed,  have  disappeared.  Thus  the  danger  that 
society  runs  from  these  vagabonds  is  considerable, 
although,  taken  individually,  these  poor  wretches  are 
rather  amorphic  than  wicked. 

81.  The  Obsessed. 

If  we  now  leave  these  degenerates,  if  we  pass  on 
from  moral  imbecility,  characterised  as  we  have  seen 
by  weakness  of  the  affective  factors  of  the  moral 
determination,  we  still  find  the  impulsive  and  the 
obsessed,  but  of  a  new  type — namely,  those  who 
resist  for  a  greater  time  their  morbid  tendencies,  who 
see  their  immoral  or  absurd  character,  but  who  ex- 
perience no  relief  until  they  have  yielded  to  them. 
Are  not  many  criminal  or  immoral  actions  the  result 
of  obsessions  ?  We  are  the  less  able  to  deny  this 
because  the  latter  are  for  the  most  part  subconscious, 
and  are  concealed  from  the  eyes  of  the  psycho- 
logist by  the  impulsive  movement,  censured  as  soon 
as  it  takes  place,  but  inevitable.  When  they  become 
conscious  they  are  already  too  strong  to  be  effec- 
tively met. 

X.  ...  is  prosecuted  for  indecent  assault.  His 
"  exhibitionist "  mania  takes  place  at  almost  regular 
periods  and  under  well-determined  circumstances; 
he  has,  as  it  were,  gusts  of  anger,  and  passes  through 
a  kind  of  crisis  which  is  excessively  painful ;  he  loses 
his  self-control,  and  gives  free  play  to  manifestations 
which  cause  him  no  gratification  but  the  sense  of 
relief  from  his  obsession. 

Sometimes  the  struggle  against  the  obsession  lasts 
for  months;  sometimes  for  a  few  days,  hours,  or 
minutes.  Some  people  experience  an  irresistible 


THE    OBSESSED.  175 

impulse  to  insult  their  relations,  to  strike  their  best 
friend,  to  throw  their  glass  or  their  napkin  at  the 
face  of  their  host,  or  to  break  some  trifling  object. 
Beings  such  as  these  occupy  an  intermediary  zone 
between  moral  sanity  and  affective  madness.1  To 
give  a  satisfactory  explanation  of  their  conduct  we 
must  evidently  connect  it  with  that  of  the  "  fixed 
ideas,"  which  are  so  numerous  in  hysteria,  neuras- 
thenia, and  all  those  forms  of  the  insanity  of  the 
degenerates  who  used  to  be  called  monomaniacs. 

It  seems  that  the  "  fixed  idea "  arises  from  the 
pathology  of  attention.2  In  normal  attention,  an 
idea,  a  sentiment,  or  an  image  is  maintained  for 
a  longer  or  shorter  period  in  the  clearness  of  con- 
scious apperception;  during  this  period  it  inhibits 
every  mental  process  which  would  challenge  its 
supremacy;  by  its  duration  it  assures  its  own  dis- 
tinctness, and  it  only  disappears  when  the  repre- 
sentation which  it  has  announced  or  prepared  has 
arrived,  and  into  which  it  is  converted,  as  it  were, 
by  a  blending  of  the  successive  moments  of  the 
conscious  life. 

For  this  to  be  so,  all  that  is  required  is  that  a  very 
strong  tendency  shall  dominate  the  mental  future; 
for  the  successive  representations  to  be  as  rich  as  the 
normal  adaptations  of  a  being  to  its  environment 
demand,  the  dominating  tendencies  of  the  mind 

1  Cf.  Cullere,  Les  Frontieres  de  la  Folie.     Paris,  1888. 

2  I  can  only  give  in  these  pages  a  summary  of  the  results  I  have 
stated  at  length  in  my  volume  on   Mental   Instability  (Alcan,   1899). 
See,  in  particular,  pp.  206  et  seq.,  on  Morbid  Stability. 

On  the  "insistent"  idea,  vide  James,  op.  cit.,  ii.  549  ;  Ribot,  op.  cit., 
p.  226 ;  Guyau,  Education  et  Htredite,  pp.  44,  56  ;  Janet,  L?Auto- 
inatisme  Psychologique,  pp.  428  et  seq.,  where  will  be  found  many 
bibliographical  references;  also  vide  his  Nevroses,  etc.,  below. — TR. 


176     THE    DETERMINISM    OF    IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

must  be  fruitful,  and  form  a  solid  body  of  appeti- 
tions,  numerous  and  in  harmony  with  the  different 
conditions  of  a  suitable  existence.  But  if  these 
tendencies  no  longer  form  a  harmonious  whole,  if 
they  are,  for  instance,  dissociated  by  those  "emotion- 
shocks,"  of  which  MM.  Janet  and  Raymond  have 
shown  the  sinister  power,  there  is  no  longer  any 
place  for  normal  attention. 

It  then  happens  that  the  unco-ordinated  tendencies 
dominate  in  turn  the  conscious  future,  and  other 
tendencies  blindly  endeavour  to  replace  them,  and 
persist  in  the  subconscious  domain,  while  the  first 
promptly  disappear  without  having  had  any  lasting 
action. 

Among  the  tendencies  which  remain  in  the  mind 
and  increase  in  power,  we  must  place  in  the  first 
rank  those  which  have  their  basis  in  the  organic 
sensations,  such  as,  for  example,  the  sexual  instinct, 
which  also  gives  an  explanation  of  the  frequency  of 
the  obsessions  and  impulses  connected  with  this 
predominant  appetite  in  animal  life. 

Let  a  favourable  occasion  present  itself,  and  im- 
mediately the  subconscious  tendency,  however  sub- 
ordinate it  may  have  been,  becomes  sovereign  and 
determines  the  irresistible  impulse.  If  it  meets  some 
obstacle,  the  subject  becomes  more  and  more  con- 
scious of  it,  and  while  it  thus  has  a  kind  of  demi- 
apperception,  the  obsession  lasts  and  a  painful 
struggle  ensues.  If  the  obstacle  is  very  great  the 
tendency  to  struggle  is  forgotten,  although  it  is  ready 
to  reappear.  That  is  why  obsessions  are  so  varied 
both  in  their  period  and  in  their  psychological  effect. 

M.  P.  Janet  admits  that  the  morbid  stability  to 
which  the  fixed  idea  is  reduced  is  certainly  the 


EXAGGERATION    OF   GOOD   SENTIMENTS.          177 

consequence  of  the  disappearance  of  the  normal 
attention.  He  always  gives  the  name  of  mental 
disaggregation  to  this  psychological  discontinuity, 
which,  as  he  himself  agrees,  favours  and  permits  im- 
pulses and  obsessions.  This  I  have  preferred  to  call 
mental  instability;  the  name,  however,  matters  but 
little.1  In  the  same  way,  it  is  to  mental  instability 
and  to  the  discontinuity  of  our  psychological  life 
consequent  on  the  downfall  of  our  normal  tendencies, 
that  the  misdemeanours  and  crimes  to  which  our  im- 
pulsives  and  occasional  delinquents  are  attracted  are 
due.  Desire  only  becomes  passion,  and  only  acquires 
excessive  and  afterwards  tyrannical  power,  by  the 
inconstancy  of  the  appetitions  and  repulsions  which 
normally  serve  as  "antagonistic  reducers."2 


82.  Exaggeration  of  Good  Sentiments. 

There  are  degenerates  who  become  misdemeanants 
by  the  morbid  exaggeration  of  sentiments  which  are 
praiseworthy  enough,  no  doubt,  but  which  encourage 
in  them  an  excessive  susceptibility.  Such  is  the  case 
of  B.E.,  a  young  fellow  of  thirty-two  years  of  age,  who 
has  twice  been  condemned  to  ten  years'  imprison- 
ment, and  was  confined  on  the  last  occasion  in  the 
criminal  asylum  of  Gaillon,  from  which  he  emerged 
with  the  reputation  of  being  violent  and  dangerous. 
At  present  he  shows  great  sensibility,  a  keen  desire 
to  lead  an  honest  life,  and  a  real  aptitude  for  the 
experience  of  the  most  delicate  emotions;  he  would 
seem  to  be  inspired  with  lofty  sentiments.  He  also 

1  Cf.  Pierre  Janet,  Nevroses  et  Idees  fixes,  pp.  34,  53,  68,  217,  218. 

2  Cf.  Instabilite  men  tale,  p.  216. 

12 


178     THE    DETERMINISM   OF   IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

shows  intelligence  and  good  will,  and  an  inclination  to 
the  good,  to  generosity,  to  sociability,  and  to  affection. 
One  is  astonished  to  hear  a  criminal  who  has  been 
punished  so  severely  eagerly  expressing  the  desires 
of  the  most  perfectly  honourable  man;  and  one  asks 
oneself  how  he  could  have  been  the  accomplice  in 
the  first  place  of  a  theft,  in  the  second  of  a  brutal 
assault,  and  finally  of  acts  of  violence  due  to  sus- 
picion of  the  administration  of  the  penitentiary  and 
of  the  alienists  who  were  attending  him. 

But  one  quickly  finds  out  that  he  is  extremely  sus- 
ceptible. The  slightest  thing  depresses  him.  One 
feels  that  he  is  not  made  'for  an  existence  such  as 
ours,  in  which  there  are  so  many  disappointments, 
so  much  distrust,  and  in  wrhich  so  much  injustice 
ought  to  be  quickly  and  rapidly  forgotten.  He  hates 
society,  which  has  made  of  him  a  thing  degraded 
for  ever  both  in  his  own  eyes  and  in  the  eyes  of 
others.  At  eighteen  years  of  age  he  was  convicted 
as  a  vagabond  and  sentenced  to  a  week's  imprison- 
ment. Ever  since  then,  he  says,  he  has  done  no 
good.  He  was  ashamed  to  present  himself  any- 
where to  ask  for  work,  and  he  became  the  prey  of 
a  few  scoundrels  who  made  him  their  accomplice. 

When  overcome  by  excitement,  he  cannot  regain  his 
self-control;  he  is  aboulic,  he  cannot  resist;  and  he  is 
violent  because  he  is  aboulic,  and  because  the  re- 
actions of  anger  find  in  him  no  "  antagonistic  re- 
ducer." Thus  he  ended  by  being  placed  under  the 
ban  of  society. 

In  his  case  the  occasional  and  the  impulsive 
criminal  are  united.  Now  the  facility  with  which 
the  moral  vertigo  takes  possession  of  him  is  really 
remarkable;  a  word  of  encouragement  or  of  praise 


MORAL   VERTIGO.  179 

makes  him  capable  of  extreme  devotion,  and  in 
certain  cases  makes  of  him  a  fanatic.  But  any  sign 
of  disapprobation  depresses  him,  and  then  for  the 
merest  trifle,  for  a  joke  or  some  foolery  of  his  com- 
panions or  his  keepers,  he  loses  his  head  and  strikes 
or  breaks  with  a  violence  of  which  one  could  hardly 
believe  him  capable.  At  the  slightest  contradiction, 
or  at  the  least  sign  of  satisfaction  with  him,  he  is 
beside  himself  with  gloom  or  delight.  He  is  very 
"  suggestible,"  and  the  reading  of  books  —  almost 
children's  books — such  as  the  wrorks  of  Jules  Verne, 
made  him  delirious  while  he  was  staying  at  Gaillon. 
He  thought  he  had  written  them,  and  he  vaguely 
imagined  a  phantom  ship  which  was  destined  to 
assure  victory  to  the  French  fleet  because  of  the 
terror  it  would  inspire  in  the  navy  of  the  enemy. 


83.  Moral  Vertigo.1 

We  see  that  such  an  aptitude  to  vividly  experience 
the  most  different  impressions,  and  to  give  way  to 
every  kind  of  suggestion,  wrould  make  of  the  best- 
intentioned  beings  misdemeanants  and  criminals; 
and  then  in  poverty,  for  example,  the  opportunity 
presents  itself  to  them  to  secure  some  temporary 
comfort,  and  the  idea  of  theft  and  murder  fascinates 
them.  They  forget  everything  else,  they  no  longer 
•experience  honourable  sentiments,  they  no  longer 
reflect.  It  is  like  a  transient  mental  alienation.  On 
the  other  hand,  their  excessive  emotional  tendencies 
predispose  them  to  fear,  anger,  exaggerated  love,  and 

1  Havelock  Ellis,  op.  cit.,  pp.  17,  91,  211,  229;  Maudsley,  Responsi- 
bility in  Mental  Disease,  pp.  59,  64,  132,  170-182;  Lombroso,  The 
^Female  Offender,  p.  310. — TR. 


iSo     THE    DETERMINISM    OF    IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

all  the  violent  sentiments  of  sudden  explosions  of 
passion. 

"We  are  led,"  says  M.  Renouvier,  "to  mark  the 
common  character  both  of  the  cases  in  which  the 
personality  is,  as  it  were,  annihilated,  its  functions 
ceasing  to  be  reflective  and  voluntary  on  all  points  at 
once,  and  of  those  (which,  however,  we  must  consider 
habitual)  in  which  vertigo  has  taken  place  on  some 
points  on  which  the  judgment  should  exact  ripe 
reflection  and  well-informed  will,  thanks  to  the 
appeal  of  motives  of  every  kind.  But  even  when 
on  the  watch,  and  in  full  possession  of  reason,  who 
has  not  experienced  exciting  temptations  of  one 
kind  or  another,  temptations  which  will  more  and 
more  tend  to  lead  into  the  abyss  a  man  whose  con- 
science would  not  be  thereby  affected  ?" 

It  is,  in  fact,  the  want  of  restraint  and  of  personal 
control  over  his  own  states  of  consciousness  which 
characterises  the  degenerate  and  explains  his  acts. 
An  analogous  moral  vertigo  may  seize  men  who  are 
healthy  in  mind  in  certain  particular  cases  in  which 
there  is  over-fatigue  of  the  brain.  In  the  same  way 
it  is  the  excuse  for  grave  or  slight  misdemeanours ;  it 
furnishes  an  explanation  of  suicide,  which,  unfortu- 
nately, is  of  too  frequent  occurrence,  and  which 
popular  feeling,  often  apart  from  all  religious  belief, 
considers  as  analogous  to  crime  or  madness,  to  such  a 
degree  that  the  children  of  a  suicide  are  repeatedly 
classed  among  those  who  are  subject  to  neuropathic 
taint. 

It  is  not  generally  anger  or  trouble  which  causes 
the  vertigo,  as  wre  have  said  before;  it  is  intellectual 
fatigue,  excessive  emotion,  and  the  struggle  against 
passions  that  are  too  active.  The  sexual  instinct, 


THE    CRIMINAL   TYPE.  l8l 

unsatisfied  or  held  within  bounds  for  too  long  a 
period,  inspires  in  some  young  men  an  unreasoning 
depression,  which  suddenly  comes  on  and  as  suddenly 
disappears ;  and  although  this  is  distinct  from 
melancholia,  it  is  often  fatal  in  its  effect.  According 
to  Laupt,  the  desire  for  death  comes  on  by  crises 
in  the  middle  of  a  happy  life.  It  arises  after  a 
sensation  of  complete  despair  and  complete  abandon- 
ment of  every  moral  energy,  coming  on  almost  in- 
stantaneously and  prostrating  the  subject.  The 
impulse  of  suicide  is  therefore  certainly  a  case  of 
moral  vertigo.  And  who  has  not  felt  in  the  course 
of  his  existence  that  profound  discouragement  and 
that  failure  of  physiological  and  mental  energy  which 
make  us  feel  for  a  moment  that  life  is  no  longer 
worth  living  ?  In  fact,  which  of  us  can  be  sure  that 
he  will  never  become  either  mad  or  a  criminal  ? 


84.  The  Criminal  Type. 

To  this  assimilation  of  people  wrho  are  ordinarily 
healthy  minded  to  criminals  or  lunatics,  an  objection 
may  be  raised,  drawn  from  the  theory  according  to 
which  all  criminals  present  the  distinctive  stigmata 
of  degenerates.1 

Lombroso  has,  in  fact,  insisted  on  the  physiological 
stigmata  of  the  criminal-born.  There  would  be  in 
that  case  an  anatomical  type  which  all  beings  pre- 
disposed or  even  devoted  to  crime  would  reproduce 
with  more  or  less  accuracy;  but  the  presence  of 
these  stigmata  in  all  criminal  degenerates  has  been 
denied. 

1  Havelock  Ellis,  op.  cit.,  pp.  49,  63,  72,  88,  102,  112;  Lombroso, 
The  Female  Offender,  passim. — TR. 


l82     THE    DETERMINISM    OF    IMMORAL    ACTIONS. 

"We  can  prove,"  say  M.  Legrain1  and  M.  Mag- 
nan,  among  others,  "  that  crime  can  take  place  with- 
out physical  stigmata;  that  individuals  who  bear  the 
most  significant  and  monstrous  physical  features  may 
have  no  vicious  tendency  whatever.  .  .  .  The  type  of 
the  criminal-born  has  been  scientifically  attacked  by 
MM.  Houze"  and  Warnots,  of  the  University  of 
Brussels.  The  anatomical  type  of  the  criminal-born 
is  a  hybrid  product  formed  by  the  junction  of  char- 
acteristics drawn  from  different  sources.  It  is  an 
artificial  type  which  must  be  rejected.  .  .  .  M. 
Struelens  has  only  found  the  stigmata  which  are  the 
marks  of  crime  in  some  three  per  cent,  of  some  5000 
individuals  examined.  .  .  .  M.  Manouvrier  has  given 
to  the  physical  stigmata  of  criminals  their  real  value. 
He  has  shown  the  difference  which  exists  between 
a  sociological  matter  such  as  crime  and  a  physio- 
logical matter  directly  connected  with  anatomy  and 
deducible  from  that  science."  It  can  never  be  denied 
that  crime  has  sometimes  psychological  conditions 
closely  connected  with  physiological  phenomena, 
which  may  have  well-defined  relations  with  ana- 
tomical peculiarities.  Having  admitted  that  much 
in  favour  of  Lombroso's  thesis,  it  only  remains  to 
point  out  the  multitude  of  cases  in  which  psychic 
troubles  are  not  accompanied  by  sensible  physio- 
logical disturbances,  and  a  fortiori  by  anatomical 
modifications.  Degeneration  has  an  infinite  number 
of  degrees  in  which  very  clear  stigmata  do  not  appear 
at  all.  On  the  other  hand,  all  degenerates  are  not 
criminals. 

We  should  lay  ourselves  open  to  the  charge   of 

1  "  L'Anthropologie  criminelle  au  Congres  de  Bruxelles  en  1892," 
Rev.  St.,  p.  14. 


IMMORAL    EFFECTS    OF    SOLIDARITY.  183 

making  a  great  blunder,  were  we  to  affirm  a  pre- 
disposition to  crime,  or  to  breach  of  the  law,  or  to 
vagabondage,  or  to  suicide,  in  people  of  exactly  the 
same  stigmata  as  those  of  the  greatest  criminals, 
people,  moreover,  who,  during  the  whole  course  of 
their  existence,  have  not  committed  a  single  criminal 
act. 

The  criminal  type  is  therefore  not  only,  as  we 
have  said  above,  an  entity  but  a  fiction.  We  simply 
find  a  type  of  degenerates  who  are  more  particularly 
to  be  found  in  the  criminal  ranks.  There  is  no 
special  class  of  misdemeanant,  clearly  separated  from 
the  majority  of  human  beings  who  ordinarily  abstain 
from  breach  of  the  law.  Any  man  may  become 
temporarily  a  criminal  just  as  he  may  become  tem- 
porarily insane.  All  that  is  necessary  is  that  mental 
vertigo  and  morbid  instability  should  be  added  to 
the  influence  of  what  we  may  call  the  social  causes 
of  crime  or  madness. 


85.  Immoral  Effects  of  Solidarity. 

Human  solidarity  may  be,  as  wre  have  seen,  a 
valuable  auxiliary  to  practical  reason,  but  it  may 
also  be  a  serious  obstacle  to  virtue.  There  is  a 
solidarity  of  criminals  as  wrell  as  a  solidarity  of 
honourable  men.  If  we  belong  to  a  perverted 
society  whose  perverse  tendencies  are  accentuated 
day  by  day  by  the  dissolution  and  the  downfall  of 
every  institution  which  once  was  the  source  of  its 
grandeur  and  its  power,  we  can  no  longer  conceive 
of  lofty  aims,  or  experience  tendencies  as  varied  and 
as  strong,  as  if  we  still  belonged  to  progressive 
society.  We  would  have  to  be  superhuman  to 


184     THE    DETERMINISM    OF   IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

struggle  successfully  against  the  perversity  around 
us.  The  best  man  ought  to  be  resigned  to  act  only 
in  the  best  possible  manner  under  given  circum- 
stances, without  aiming  at  an  absolutely  good  action. 
As  for  the  man  whose  character  is  weak,  whose 
will  is  feeble,  and  whose  intellect  and  sensibility 
have  not  been  normally  developed,  he  very  rapidly 
becomes  a  victim  to  the  surrounding  perversity. 

Lombroso  has  remarked  that,  as  a  rule,  the 
criminal  hates  solitude  and  cannot  live  without 
companions.  The  need  of  entering  into  relations 
with  individuals  who  can  guide  him,  direct  him, 
and  dominate  him,  constitutes,  as  Janet  has  re- 
marked, one  of  the  features  of  the  character  of  the 
hysterical  and  weak-minded  subject.  Feeble  in- 
tellects are  therefore  more  exposed  than  normal 
intellects  to  the  pernicious  influence  of  certain 
companions,  or  of  certain  sects,  or  of  the  crowd,  or 
of  morally  degraded  collectivities.  They  say  that 
in  Brazil  among  the  half-breeds,  who,  as  a  rule, 
show  a  very  marked  characteristic  of  hereditary 
ferocity,  and  in  whom  barbarism  seems  to  increase 
as  the  effect  of  a  kind  of  social  disequilibrium, 
the  most  monstrous  crimes  are  as  a  rule  committed 
by  the  least  intelligent  of  their  number.  In  places 
that  are  most  propitious  to  the  growth  of  vice,  in 
the  lower  quarters  of  the  great  towns,  bands  of 
criminals  are  formed  by  an  easy  and  ready  recruiting 
of  all  the  inferior  beings,  who  have  grown  up  in  a 
common  poverty  of  moral  instincts  and  a  complete 
absence  of  elevating  sentiments. 

The  criminal  class  turns  to  account  the  instinct 
of  sociability,  of  solidarity,  and  of  tendencies  to 
obedience ;  it  exercises  sometimes  a  veritable 


EFFECTS    OF    HEREDITY,    ALCOHOLISM,    ETC.     185 

tyranny  over  its  members,  and  even  over  its  leaders, 
who  are  the  docile  tools  of  the  community,  and  who 
exercise  in  their  turn  the  most  brutal  or  the  most 
insidious  forms  of  constraint  on  wavering  or  passive 
individuals. 

The  mob  is  like  a  torrent  which  sweeps  away 
everything  in  its  path.  If  we  form  part  of  a  multi- 
tude assembled  by  chance,  or  of  an  elected  assembly, 
we  do  not  belong  to  ourselves  so  completely,  our 
intellect  is  less  clear,  our  sentiments  are  not  so  lofty, 
our  will  is  not  so  strong,  and  we  are  less  worthy  from 
all  points  of  view  than  when  we  think,  feel,  and  act 
in  isolation.  No  doubt  we  may  give  way  to  noble 
impulses,  we  may  experience  and  communicate  to 
others  noble  passions ;  but,  as  a  rule,  we  run  the 
risk  of  letting  ourselves  be  carried  away  and 
dominated  by  confused  visions,  which  neither  corre- 
spond to  the  best  that  can  be  perceived,  nor  to 
what  we  would  best  prefer  if  we  could  freely  dispose 
of  ourselves. 


86.  Effects  of  Heredity,  A  Icoholism,  and  Social 
Disturbances  in  general. 

In  addition  to  the  influences  exercised  by  the 
criminal  class  and  the  crowd,  heredity  plays  so 
considerable  a  role  in  the  determination  of  our 
fundamental  tendencies,  that  we  cannot  overlook 
the  part  that  is  taken  in  the  genesis  of  crime  or 
of  misdemeanour  by  hereditary  tendencies,  and  by 
the  social  environment  from  which  those  tendencies 
have  emerged. 

Degeneration,  so  far  as  it  is  a  partial  or  general 
weakening  of  the  faculties  of  adaptation  of  the  being 


l86     THE    DETERMINISM    OF    IMMORAL   ACTIONS. 

to  its  environment,  of  the  power  of  work,  and  of 
resistance  to  nervous  or  psychic  troubles,  has  often 
social  causes,  especially  when  it  affects  a  large 
number  of  individuals  of  the  same  age  and  of  the 
same  environment. 

In  the  first  rank  of  the  social  causes  of  degene- 
ration we  must  place  alcoholism,1  the  prejudices 
against  suitable  choice  in  marriage,  and  intellectual 
and  professional  over-work.  "  The  choice  of  a  wife, 
or  of  a  husband,"  says  M.  Goblot  (a  propos  of  my 
treatise  on  the  determining  influences  of  madness), 
"  is  determined  far  too  much  by  worldly  conven- 
tions and  material  interests.  How  does  a  man  get 
into  such  a  state  as  to  require  in  his  wife 
neither  health,  beauty,  intellect,  nor  heart  ?  What 
is  also  the  mystery  of  the  strange  seduction  of 
alcohol,  a  seduction  which  continues  to  be  prevalent 
in  spite  of  our  knowledge  of  its  danger  ?  How  can 
the  desire  of  '  getting  on  '  in  order  to  acquire  wealth, 
and  of  '  bettering  ourselves '  by  depriving  ourselves 
for  that  purpose  of  all  enjoyment  and  all  repose — 
how  can  it  be  so  powerful  as  to  check  the  instinct 
of  self-preservation  ?  These  are  interesting  problems 
in  social  psychology." 

We  cannot  pretend  to  solve  these  excessively 
complex  problems  in  a  day,  but  we  may  fearlessly 
assert  that  the  causes  we  seek  are  not  merely 
psychological,  and  that  the  morbid  phenomena  thus 
pointed  out  are  due  to  more  than  individual  per- 
version, in  fact  to  a  social  state  of  disturbance  and 
disintegration ;  and  that,  precisely  because  a  kind  of 
fatality  seems  to  weigh  on  individuals,  and  because 
the  will  is  powerless  to  re-act  against  a  fatal  current, 

1  Vide  my  Causes  societies  de  la  Folie.     Alcan,  1901. 


EFFECTS    OF    HEREDITY,    ALCOHOLISM,    ETC.     187 

we  can  guess  that  this  current  borrows  its  force  from 
sociological  determinism.  And  besides,  it  is  known 
that  criminality  and  immorality  increase  in  all  periods 
of  political  disturbance  and  social  "  anomia."  M. 
Durkheim  has  shown  that  the  principal  cause  of 
suicide  is  the  variable  state  of  disintegration  of 
society,  and  that  the  frequency  of  suicides  is  in 
inverse  ratio  to  the  power  of  politico-religious  or- 
ganisation ;  so  that  the  Catholic  being  more  strongly 
integrated  than  the  Protestant  communities,  place 
more  obstacles  in  the  way  of  suicide.1  What  M. 
Durkheim  says  of  suicide  we  may  repeat  of  all 
immoral  acts. 

There  is  no  doubt,  then,  that  a  healthy  social 
organisation  can  remedy  immorality,  and  if  we 
consider,  in  addition,  that  psychological  conditions 
alone  can  give  a  complete  determination  to  moral 
obligation  by  assigning  a  supreme  end  to  reasonable 
conduct,  we  shall  be  convinced  of  the  necessity  for 
the  ethico-sociological  researches  which  will  follow. 
Their  object,  in  fact,  is  to  bring  us  to  a  conception  of  the 
social  ideal  from  which  will  be  eradicated  those  principal 
causes  of  crime  or  lawlessness  that  are  fundamentally 
identical  with  the  social  causes  of  madness. 

1  Durkheim,  Le  Suicide,  pp.  149  et  seq. ;  Morselli,  S^^.icidet  pp. 
119  130,  and  Tables  XVI.  and  XVII.— TR. 


PART   III. 

THE   SOCIAL    IDEAL. 

I.  SOCIAL  EVOLUTION. 

87.  The  Present  State  of  Sociology — 88.  Social  Statics 
and  Dynamics — 89.  The  Evolution  of  the  Family — 90. 
The  Matriarchate  and  the  Primitive  Condition  of 
Woman — 91.  The  Primitive  Condition  of  Children — 92. 
The  "  P atria  Potcstas  "  and  the  Dissolution  of  the  Family 
— 93.  The  Future  of  the  Family — 94.  Animal  Societies — 
95.  Political  Life  and  the  Struggle  of  Classes  —  96. 
The  Idea  of  Equality — 97.  Governments—  98.  Plutocracy 
— 99.  Political  Evolution  and  Law — 100.  The  Law  of 
Contract. 

II.  SOCIAL  EVOLUTION  (Continued], 

101.  The  Primitive  Economic  State — 102.  Economic 
Evolution — 103.  Division  of  Labour — 104.  Association — 
105.  Slavery  and  Property — 106.  Properly — 107.  Capital 
and  Labour — 108.  Collective  Sentiments — 109.  Differ- 
entiation of  the  Primitive  Sentiments — 110.  The  Evolu- 
tion of  Sociability — 1 1 1.  The  Religion  of  Humanity  and 
of  the  Unknowable — 112.  Sociological  A nticipations. 

III.  THE  SOCIAL  IDEAL. 

113.  Individualism  and  Altruism — 114.  The  Over- 
Man — 115.  Sacrifice  of  the  Unfit— u 6.  The  Gospel  of 
Tolstoi — 117.  Renunciation — 118.  The  Consequences  of 
Non-resistance  to  Evil — 119.  The  Necessity  of  Conflict— 
120.  Despotism — 121.  The  Meek — 122.  The  Aristocracy 
— 123.  Importance  of  the  Theory  of  Rights. 

IV.  RIGHTS. 

124.  The  Foundation  of  Rights— 125.  Natural  Right — 
126.  Metaphysical  Right  and  Dignity — 127.  Rights  of 
Social  Function — 128.  Justice  and  Devotion — 129.  Justice 


THE    PRESENT    STATE    OF    SOCIOLOGY.  189 

and  Charily — 130.  7'ke  Right  of  Property — 131.  The 
Share  of  the  Community — 132.  Property  and  Rejorm — 
133.  The  Hereditary  Transmission  of  Property. 

V.  THE  STATE. 

1 3  4.  The  Role  of  the  State — 135.  Theories  of  Sovereignty — 
136.  Summary  of  the  Theories — 137.  Relative  Sovereignty 
and  the  Social  Contract — 138.  Duties  of  the  State — 139. 
The  State  and  Associations — 140.  The  State  as  Educator 
—141.  The  State  as  Judge. 

VI.  THE  ECONOMIC  ORGANISATION. 

142.  Competition — 143.  Subordination  of  the  Economic 
Order  to  a  Higher  Order— 144.  The  Role  of  the  State 
—  145.  The  State  Principle  and  the  Corvee — 146. 
Taxation — 147.  Solidarity  in  the  Economic  Order — 148. 
The  Wages  System — 149.  Co-operation — 150.  The  Work 
of  Women  and  Children — 151.  Value  of  the  Workman — 
152.  The  Choice  of  a  Profession — 153.  The  Rights  and 
Duties  of  the  Workman. 

VII.  THE    FAMILY,    FRIENDSHIP,    AND    THE    COLLECTIVE 

SENTIMENTS. 

154.  The  Rights  of  Woman — 155.  Martiage — 156.  The 
Co- Education  and  Equality  of  the  Sexes — 157.  Divorce 
and  Duties  towards  Children — 158.  Duties  of  Children — 
159.  Friendship  and  Fraternity — 160.  Man  in  Relation 
to  Animals — 161.  Genuine  Human  Sentiments. 

I. 

SOCIAL  EVOLUTION. 

87.  The  Present  State  oj  Sociology. 

SOCIOLOGY  is  not  advanced  enough  for  us  to  be  able 
to  register  here,  as  results  definitely  acquired  by  the 
science,  a  whole  mass  of  data  on  what  one  might  call 
the  anatomy,  psychology,  and  ontogeny  of  societies. 
We  cannot  yet  say  what  are  the  organs  and  the 


SOCIAL    EVOLUTION. 

functions  indispensable  to  social  life,  with  as  much 
precision  and  certainty  as  we  can  in  the  case  of  the 
organs  and  functions  necessary  to  psychic  or  bio- 
logical activity.  However,  sociological  ideas  are 
already  sufficiently  widespread  for  us  not  to 
suppose  any  longer,  as  they  seemed  to  suppose  in 
the  eighteenth  century,  that  social  life  is  something 
artificial,  and  is  the  product  of  a  human  invention, 
the  effect  of  a  social  contract  which  was  not  auto- 
matically produced. 

We  know  that  social  relations  form  part  of  natural 
relations ;  that  some  of  them  are  necessary ;  that 
others  are  laws  proper  to  collective  life  and  the 
evolution  of  societies — in  short,  that  all  these  rela- 
tions, with  most  of  which  we  are  unfamiliar,  will 
be  some  day  established  and  will  constitute  the 
object  of  a  real  science. 

It  may  therefore  be  claimed  that  it  would  be 
more  prudent  to  put  off  to  that  day,  be  it  more  or 
less  remote,  the  solution  of  the  problem  that  we  are 
setting  ourselves  here — that  of  the  moral  organisa- 
tion of  social  life — until  this  problem  can  be  attacked 
by  men  who  are  thoroughly  familiar  with  the  collec- 
tive laws  of  life  and  of  evolution.  But  no  science  is 
complete  even  if  it  serve  already  as  a  basis  for  a 
practical  theory.  Medicine  is  contemporary  with  the 
first  physiological  researches,  and  if  we  are  to  wait 
to  act  until  we  are  perfectly  informed  we  shall  never 
act  at  all.  There  would  be  this  great  danger  in  not 
giving  a  provisional  solution  to  the  practical  prob- 
lems which  lie  before  us,  whatever  might  be  the 
present  poverty  of  our  knowledge  of  sociology, 
namely,  that  ethics  would  continue  to  be  purely 
individual,  to  concern  only  an  abstract  being,  since 


SOCIAL  STATICS  AND  DYNAMICS.        IQI 

the  social  being  takes  an  ever  larger  place  in  our 
personality.  To  allow  the  traditional  morality  to 
subsist  is  to  allow  a  phantom  to  subsist  that  has 
no  action  on  morals ;  it  were  better,  then,  to  substi- 
tute for  it  a  solution  in  conformity  with  the  scientific 
truth  of  to-day.  Besides,  the  scientific  truth  of  to- 
morrow, and  we  must  not  disguise  it  from  ourselves, 
will  be  found  too  restricted  and  too  remote  to  satisfy 
the  requirements  of  reality. 

To  believe  in  a  perpetual  transformation  of  moral 
theories  is  by  no  means  the  same  thing  as  a  confes- 
sion of  scepticism.  It  is  only  inert  things  which  do 
not  undergo  evolution.  Morality,  the  theory  of  social 
activity,  and  of  individual  or  collective  life  in  society, 
should  be  subject  to  shifting  change  like  life  itself. 
Like  the  living  being  it  should  evolve,  following  the 
progress  of  the  human  mind,  and,  in  particular,  the 
progress  of  science.  Logicians  may  boast  that  their 
art  has  not  changed  since  the  days  of  Aristotle. 
Either  logic  has  not  followed  the  progress  of  the 
scientific  method,  or  it  has  no  relation  to  that 
method,  and  therefore  has  no  object  and  is  a  use- 
less art.  It  were  better  to  admit  that  it  has  changed, 
and  that  it  will  again  be  modified.  The  moralist  in 
the  same  way  has  changed  and  will  change.  At  most, 
the  best-informed  moralist  can  boast  that  he  is  writing 
for  his  generation,  unless  he  keeps  within  the  sphere 
of  trivialities  and  general  theories  those  immortal 
abstractions  which  are  valid  as  classical  types  for 
all  times  and  all  places. 

88.  Social  Statics  and  Dynamics. 

Auguste  Comte  has  distinguished  between  the 
statics  and  dynamics  of  social  science.  Adapt- 


SOCIAL    EVOLUTION. 

ing  and  slightly  modifying  this  view,  it  seems 
legitimate  to  consider  separately  the  totality  of 
functions  and  organisms  that  are  indispensable  to 
all  social  life  and  to  evolution  properly  so  called ; 
to  construct  on  the  one  hand  the  anatomy  and  the 
physiology,  and  on  the  other  hand  the  ontogeny  of 
societies.  But  what  are  the  principal  institutions 
that  are  indispensable  to  all  social  life  ?  They  are 
evidently  those  which  correspond  to  the  tendencies 
that  are  essential  to  every  human  aggregate;  and 
comparative  sociology  alone  can  instruct  us. 

In  all  civilisations  we  find  religious  institutions. 
We  discover  them  at  the  very  origin  of  social  life. 
They  are  everywhere  closely  connected  with  in- 
tellectual tendencies  (which  will  become  scientific 
tendencies)  and  with  political  tendencies.  The 
latter  (scientific  and  political)  are  distinct  from  the 
former,  and  give  rise  to  entirely  different  institutions, 
but  the  necessity  and  the  universality  of  these  institu- 
tions is  not  a  matter  of  debate,  even  although  they 
have  been  involved  in  their  origin  in  religious  institu- 
tions.1 And  so  it  is  with  ethical  tendencies — tend- 
encies to  games,  to  holidays,  and  collective  manifesta- 
tions of  joy  or  sorrow. 

Outside  the  religious  life  there  is  little  else  at 
the  outset  but  the  sexual  relations  and  economic  life. 
The  institutions  which  harmonise  with  the  sexual 
appetite  were  not  long  before  they  appeared,  if  it 
is  true  that  there  ever  was  a  social  phase  of 
complete  promiscuity;2  exogamy  and  endogamy  show 
us  what  social  importance  was  attached  to  the 

1  Vide  Section  5. 

2  Westermarck,   History  of  Marriage^    chap,    iv.-v.  ;    Letourneau, 
1 he  Evolution  of  Marriage ,  chap.  iii. — TK. 


SOCIAL    STATICS    AND    DYNAMICS.  193 

regulations  of  unions  between  individuals  of  dif- 
ferent sexes.1  As  for  the  phenomena  of  economic 
life,  they  have  become  of  ever-increasing  complexity, 
starting  first  of  all  from  a  simple  tendency  to  the 
search  in  common  for  nutriment  and  shelter. 
Exchange  has  become  commerce  with  its  multiple 
institutions.  Slavery,  serfdom,  domesticity,  com- 
pulsory or  free  association,  have  in  turn  been  the 
consequences  of  the  social  organisation  of  work ;  but 
we  cannot  say  of  any  one  of  these  institutions  taken 
in  particular  that  it  is  of  such  social  necessity  that 
it  must  never  disappear.  On  the  contrary,  its  ap- 
pearance at  only  certain  places  and  at  certain  times, 
its  incessant  transformations,  are  each  in  turn  signs 
of  its  fugitive  character. 

And  so  it  is  that  the  various  forms  of  property,  the 
various  legal  institutions,  as  well  as  the  various  forms 
of  government,  have  only  a  relative  importance  in 
the  eyes  of  those  who  seek  for  what  is  most  stable  in 
every  society. 

The  first  evolution  of  economic  life  gave  rise  under 
certain  circumstances  to  strong  tendencies  to  military 
life  and  organisation ;  but  it  cannot  be  affirmed  that 
all  societies  passed  through  the  military  phase  before 
entering  the  industrial  phase.  Military  institutions 
can  only  correspond  to  transient  needs,  or  may 
constitute  simple  phenomena  of  reversion. 

We  see  how  little  in  the  way  of  deeply  rooted 
tendencies  remains  beneath  the  variety  of  transi- 
tory social  institutions;  but  love  and  hunger,  which, 
as  Schiller  said,  cannot  fail  to  influence  the 
world  \vhile  philosophers  and  moralists  are  dis- 
puting, compel  us  to  attack  the  problem  of  the 

1  Spencer,  Principles  of  Sociology  ^  chap.  xx.  4. — TR. 


IQ4  SOCIAL   EVOLUTION. 

moral    organisation    of   the    sexual    and    economic 
relations. 

The  disinterested  sentiments,  the  needs  of  heart 
and  mind,  religious,  aesthetic,  and  scientific  tenden- 
cies, compel  us  at  least  to  seek  for  the  means  of  life 
in  common,  by  giving  to  those  sentiments,  needs, 
and  tendencies  a  legitimate  satisfaction.  And  finally, 
the  universal  existence  of  social  constraint,  and  of 
political  power  and  organisation,  compel  us  to  study 
the  relations  of  the  State  and  the  individual,  and 
to  examine  political  life  from  the  moral  point  of 
view.  For  that  purpose  we  ought  as  a  preliminary 
to  consider  the  evolution  of  law  and  morals  in  the 
family,  in  the  city,  and  in  the  State  —  economic 
evolution  and  the  evolution  of  the  sentiments. 

89.  The  Evolution  of  the  Family. 

Auguste  Comte  considered  the  family  as  the  social 
unit  v  par  excellence.  Before  and  after  him  most 
moralists  have  insisted  on  the  close  relations  of 
family  and  of  social  life,  as  if  the  family  were  the 
prototype  of  every  collective  organisation  based  upon 
natural  relations.  We  know  that  Aristotle  compares, 
in  his  Politics?  the  different  kinds  of  government  to 
the  different  modes  of  authority  which  can  be  realised 
in  the  family  by  the  subordination  of  the  wife  to  the 
husband,  of  the  children  to  the  father,  and  of  the 
slaves  to  the  master.  The  father  is  therefore  con- 
sidered as  a  monarch,  and  that  by  nature.  Many 
modern  writers  have  shared  the  mistake  of  Aristotle 
on  this  point,  and  have  held  that  the  family  type  is 
one  and  unchanging. 

1  Book  I.,  chap,  iii.— TR. 


THE    EVOLUTION    OF   THE    FAMILY.  195 

The  social  evolution  of  different  races  shows  us,  on 
the  contrary,  that  the  aspect  of  the  family  inces- 
santly varies.  Contemporary  sociology  has  even 
endeavoured  to  subordinate  the  evolution  of  the 
family  to  the  general  law  laid  down  by  Spencer, 
in  virtue  of  which  everything  passes  from  the  homo- 
geneous to  the  heterogeneous,  from  the  indefinite  to 
the  definite,  from  the  simple  to  the  complex,  and  so 
on.  A  kind  of  promiscuity  of  the  sexes  has  often 
been  admitted  as  the  primitive  state  anterior  to 
family  life.1 

Bachofen,2  in  1861,  expounded  the  doctrine  accord- 
ing to  which  the  state  of  promiscuity  must  have 
succeeded  the  matriarchate,  the  regime  of  the  femi- 
nine rule,  or  rather  the  preponderance,  from  the 
legal  point  of  view,  of  the  relations  based  upon 
parentage  by  woman.  Many  authors  have  given 
direct  or  indirect  proofs  of  the  existence  of  a  matri- 
archal phase,  the  levirate,  the  ambil  anak,3  etc. 
According  to  M.  Durkheim  and  according  to  MacLen- 
nan,4  to  promiscuity  would  have  succeeded  in  the 
organisation  by  clans  a  rudiment  of  family  institu- 
tions with  endogamic  or  exogamic  polyandry.  Poly- 
gamy would  only  come  later,  immediately  preceding 
the  monogamic  family  of  races  at  present  the  most 
civilised.  However,  opinions  are  very  much  divided 
on  the  origin  of  the  family.  It  may  be  stated  at  the 
outset  that  the  state  of  promiscuity  is  at  least  an- 
terior to  the  formation  of  human  societies.  Already 

1  It  has  also  been  often  denied;  see,  e.g.,  Westermarck,  History  of 
Marriage.  — TR. 

2  Cf.  Das  Mutterrecht. 

3  Cf.  Mazzarella,  La  Condizione  giuridica  del  Marito  nel  Famiglia 
matriarcale. 

4  Studies  in  Ancient  History,     London,  1878, 


ig6  SOCIAL   EVOLUTION. 

in  animal  societies  we  find,  as  M.  Espinas  has  shown, 
very  stable  forms  of  conjugal  existence:  most  birds 
are  monogamic ; l  the  male  and  the  female  experience 
for  each  other  a  disinterested  affection,  which  survives 
the  attraction  of  their  first  meeting,  and  which  is 
prolonged  far  beyond  the  duration  of  their  union.2 

Could  not  the  stability  of  sexual  unions  which 
increases  with  the  degree  of  intelligence  of  the 
animals,  have  been  possible  from  the  beginning,  at 
least -in  certain  human  races  ?  It  is  very  likely  that, 
as  M.  Lalande3  thinks  with  Darwin  and  Sir  Henry 
Maine,4  the  family  springs  directly,  perfectly  dif- 
ferentiated and  perfectly  formed,  from  the  physio- 
logical conditions  of  reproduction.5 


go.  The  Matriarchate  and  the  Primitive  Condition  of 
Woman. 

To  the  argument  of  the  disciples  of  Bachofen,  who 
concede  a  matriarchal  phase  necessarily  preceding 
the  patriarchal,  is  opposed  the  opinion  that  the  matri- 
archal forms,  and  the  ambil  anak  in  particular, 
although  observed  by  Mazzarella  in  more  than  one 
hundred  and  thirty  cases  among  the  most  diverse 
races  of  every  country  in  the  world,  are  perverted 

1  Societ'es  animates,  p.  424.  2  Ibid.^  p.  429. 

3  La  Dissolution  opposee  a  /  Evolution,  p.  312. 

4  "  If  it  is  really  to  be  accepted  as  a  social  fact,  the  explanation 
assuredly  lies  among  the  secrets  and  mysteries  of  our  nature." — Village 
Communities,  p.  15.    Also  vide  Early  Law  and  Ancient  Custom. — TR. 

5  According  to  Marro,    Trans,   of  Ethnog.  Sot:.,  xi.  p.   35,   among 
the  Andamans,   a  woman  who  resists  the  conjugal  embraces  of  any 
member  of  the  tribe  exposes  herself  to  severe  punishment.     Is  this  a 
vestige  of  the  so-called  primitive  promiscuity?     Is  it  not  rather  a  sign  of 
decadence?    (Cf.   Letourneavi,  op.  cit.,  p.  43,  Trans,  of  Ethnog.  Soc.^ 
N.S.  ii.,  p.  35,  v.  p.  45.—  TR.) 


PRIMITIVE    CONDITION    OF   WOMAN.  IQ7 

forms  of  the  primitive  family  institution,  modes 
posterior  to  the  normal  modes  of  family  existence, 
and  products  of  social  dissolution. 

Besides,  not  only  may  a  unique  beginning  of  family 
evolution  be  argued,  but  several  kinds  of  beginning, 
corresponding  to  the  different  types  of  the  primitive 
family.  Grosse l  seems  to  have  correctly  distinguished 
the  family  of  the  hunter  from  that  of  the  shepherd  or 
the  farmer,  either  inferior  or  superior.  Exogamy  or 
endogamy  has  had  to  depend,  just  as  the  existence 
or  the  non-existence  of  the  matriarchate  has  had  to 
depend,  on  entirely  different  economical  conditions, 
which  have  profoundly  affected  the  social  and  legal 
position  of  woman,  a  position  which  varies  so  con- 
siderably at  different  stages  of  civilisation. 

M.  Letourneau2  thinks  that  in  all  primitive 
societies  the  woman  represents  the  domestic  animal, 
the  beast  of  burden  of  more  advanced  societies;  that 
she  is  treated  as  a  slave,  and  that  this  is  one  of  the 
reasons  why  slavery  was  established  at  such  a  late 
period  in  the  course  of  social  evolution.  In  Australia, 
among  the  clans,  slavery  is  unknown.  Women  are 
reduced  to  serfdom,  are  overworked,  and  ill-treated. 
The  analogy  to  the  beast  of  burden  is  complete. 
Schurtz3  confirms  this  evidence.  According  to 
Ratzel,4  the  woman  is  considered  by  her  husband 
as  a  commodity;  she  is  taken  without  her  consent 
among  the  Dieyeries,  the  natives  of  Powell's  Creek 
on  Herbert  River,  on  the  west  side  of  the  Gulf  of 
Carpentaria.  She  is  exchanged  at  the  whim  of  her 

1  Die  Formen  der  Familie.     Leipzig,  1896. 

2  L' Evolution  de  FEsclavage  (1897),  pp.  27  et  seq. 
:5  Katechisnms  der  Volkerkunde  (1893),  p.  139. 

4  Vblkerkunde,  ii.  pp.  66  et  se<j. 


ig8  SOCIAL    EVOLUTION. 

brothers  or  relations.  She  may  be  sold  or  exchanged 
by  her  husband  when  she  no  longer  works  according 
to  his  liking.  She  may  be  slain  without  any  legal 
sanction,  when  she  is  no  longer  able  to  work,  or 
when  food  is  not  forthcoming  for  her  nourishment; 
and  finally,  after  the  death  of  her  husband,  she  be- 
comes the  property  of  his  brother. 

But  Dr.  Nieboer1  refuses  to  see  "only  these  bad 
features  of  the  case."  Sometimes,  even  in  Australia, 
the  wishes  of  the  women  are  taken  into  considera- 
tion, both  in  family  life  and  in  marriage.  There  are 
numerous  cases  of  women  who  have  had  a  real  in- 
fluence over  their  husbands.2  The  levirate  exists, 
according  to  Fraser  and  Dawson,  among  the  natives 
of  New  South  Wales  and  of  West  Victoria.  "  When 
a  married  man  dies  his  brother  is  obliged  to  marry 
the  widow  if  she  has  a  family,  to  protect  her,  and  to 
take  care  of  the  children  of  his  brother."  Here, 
then,  is  a  medley  of  customs  apparently  in  complete 
opposition,  the  one  favourable  to  the  doctrine  of  the 
omnipotence  of  the  husband,  and  the  other  rather 
opposed  to  it.  Signs  of  the  primitive  slavery  of 
woman  always  predominate,  however,  and  that  in 
the  tribes  of  North  America  as  well  as  in  the  clans 
of  Australia.  The  women  of  the  Ojibeway  Indians, 
according  to  Jones,  do  the  hardest  work,  receive  the 
worst  nourishment,  and  can  barely  claim  a  place  in 
the  wigwam.  Mackenzie3  quotes  numerous  instances 
of  the  slavery  in  which  women  of  other  Indian  tribes, 

1  Dr.   Nieboer,    "  Slavery  as  an    Industrial   System,"  Ethnological 
Researches.     The  Hague,  1900. 

2  Letourneau,  op.  cit.,  pp.  190,  263-265. — TR. 

3  Voyages  from  Montreal  through  the  Continent  of  North  America 
(1802),  vol.  i.  pp.  147  et  seq.'j  vol.  ii.  pp.  15  et  seq. 


PRIMITIVE    CONDITION    OF   WOMAN.  199 

the  Sioux,  the  Apaches,  etc.,  are  kept.  In  Melanesia 
the  condition  is  that  of  the  severest  slavery.  Women 
are  estimated  according  to  the  amount  of  work  they 
can  do.  In  Oceania,  polygamy  is  very  often  only  a 
means  for  purely  economic  ends. 

And  further,  according  to  Dr.  Nieboer,  wherever 
the  situation  of  women  is  improved,  it  is  because 
wealth  or  easy  circumstances  allow  the  husbands 
to  entrust  to  slaves  or  servants  the  work  which 
their  wives  would  otherwise  have  been  compelled 
to  do.  It  would  not,  therefore,  be  surprising  to 
find  that  in  many  cases  family  evolution  began 
with  feminine  slavery,  and  that  in  some  cases 
only  has  woman  had  from  the  beginning  a  social 
and  legal  position,  if  not  superior,  at  any  rate  equal 
to  that  of  man.  Besides,  the  existence  of  the  matri- 
archal regime  cannot  prove  the  primitive  superiority 
of  woman  to  man.  If  the  transmission  of  property 
takes  place  by  the  female  line,  if  children  remain 
attached  to  their  mother,  and  therefore  are  submitted 
to  the  authority  of  her  immediate  parents — if,  in 
short,  family  life  as  a  whole  has  for  its  pivot 
maternity — such  a  state  of  things  is  perfectly  natural, 
especially  among  warriors  and  hunters,  where  the 
men  are  almost  always  away  from  the  home.  It 
is  none  the  less  natural  that  this  should  not  be 
the  case  among  races  leading  an  agricultural  life, 
and  that  patriarchal  manners  should  be  established, 
if  not  at  once,  at  any  rate  much  sooner  among  the 
latter  than  among  the  former. 

As  for  the  slavery  of  man,  the  situation  created 
by  the  ambil  anak,  in  which  the  husband  is  the 
servant,  the  slave,  without  any  rights  over  his 
children,  we  consider  that  such  a  mode  of  family 


2OO  SOCIAL   EVOLUTION. 

existence  may  have  been,  and  must  have  been, 
realised  where  strong  men  left  one  by  one  a  poor 
clan  which  was  unable  to  give  them  food  and  work, 
to  betake  themselves  to  rich  and  prosperous  countries 
where  they  were  treated  as  strangers,  and  therefore 
deprived  of  every  right,  even  over  their  own  children. 
It  does  not  follow,  as  M.  Mazzarella  believes,  that  the 
ambil  anak  has  everywhere  constituted  a  necessary 
phase  of  the  evolution  of  the  family. 

We  may,  therefore,  admit  that  at  the  beginning 
of  different  civilisations  the  condition  of  woman  has 
been  in  most  cases  an  inferior  condition. 

91.  The  Primitive  Condition  of  Children. 

Was  this  not  also  the  case  with  children  ?  We 
seem  to  have  been  much  more  preoccupied,  in  the 
environment  in  which  the  theory  of  the  matriarchate 
has  assumed  such  importance,  with  the  condition 
of  children  than  that  of  parents.  However,  Dr. 
Steinmetz  has  recently  gathered  together  in  an  in- 
teresting study1  the  data  which  are  to  be  found 
in  the  works  of  Bancroft,  Krause,  Burckhardt,  Von 
Middendorf,  Sohm,  Puchta,  and  others,  on  this 
question. 

He  has  shown  what  degree  of  development  has 
been  attained  among  savages  by  what  the  Romans 
called  "patria  potestas."  It  is  said  that  at  Flores 
the  children  of  the  richest  families  are  treated 
as  slaves  as  long  as  their  father  is  living,  that 
they  figure  as  slaves  both  at  public  festivals  and 
at  the  funeral  rites  of  their  father,  and  that  this  is 

1  "Das  Verhaltniss  zwischen  Eltern  und  Kindern  bei  den  Natur- 
volken,"  Zeilschrift  fiir  Socialwissenschaft,  I. 


DISSOLUTION    OF   THE    FAMILY.  2OI 

evidently  the  external  sign  of  a  rigorous  paternal 
authority.  The  Apaches,  the  Botocodos,  the  Be- 
douins, and  the  Samoyedes  have,  as  the  ancient 
Roman  had,  the  power  of  life  and  death  (jus  mice 
ac  necis)  over  their  children.  They  use  them  for 
their  own  purposes  as  chattels  or  domestic  animals. 
Everywhere  the  matriarchal  regime  exists,  children 
owe  entire  obedience  and  complete  devotion  to  their 
maternal  uncle  in  particular,  and  he  has  over  them 
infinitely  more  rights  than  their  own  father.  To  him 
they  owe  everything,  and  they  have  a  right  to  nothing. 

92.  The  "Patria  Potestas"  and  the  Dissolution  of 
the  Family. ^ 

The  point  of  departure  of  female  evolution  seems 
therefore  to  be  the  despotism  of  the  head  of  the 
family,  the  slavery  of  the  component  elements, 
women  and  children  in  most  cases,  but  husband 
and  children  under  circumstances  which,  if  not 
abnormal  and  exceptional,  are  at  least  rare.  And 
further,  the  elements  of  the  family  were  ill  defined 
at  the  outset.  The  family  was  included  in  a  more 
or  less  vast  aggregate,  and  itself  very  often  com- 
prised servants  whose  condition  and  lot  were  but 
very  little  different  from  that  of  the  other  members 
of  the  family  who  were  united  by  "ties  of  blood." 

In  proportion  as  the  authority  of  the  chief  is 
strengthened,  we  see  the  family  form  a  much  more 
independent  whole  with  its  own  traditions,  its  own 
gods,  its  own  worship,  its  own  rights,  and  its  own 
government.  It  becomes,  as  it  were,  a  house  com- 
pletely closed  to  most  external  influences  and  almost 

1  Maine,  Ancient  Law,  pp.  133-146. — TR. 


2O2  SOCIAL    EVOLUTION. 

self-sufficient.  Then  the  great  family  is  dissolved 
to  make  way  for  small  families,  containing  fewer 
elements,  and  having  between  them  relationships 
which  become  better  and  better  defined.  Paternal 
and  marital  power  become  weakened,  and  at  the 
present  day  in  the  most  civilised  countries  the  family 
whose  cohesion  reposes  purely  and  simply  on  the 
authority  of  the  head,  is  in  a  fair  way  to  dissolution. 
Thus  it  may  be  considered  as  having  reached  the 
most  advanced  stage  in  general  evolution.  In  the 
times  of  the  Punic  wars,  says  M.  Lalande,1  respect 
for  the  family  is  at  least  as  strong  as  respect 
for  the  State;  discipline  always  reigns  on  the 
domestic  hearth.  In  our  days  respect  for  parents 
and  for  the  husband  loses  its  ancient  character, 
which  was  derived  from  fear  of  the  tyrant.  Woman 
has  progressively  freed  herself  from  the  narrow 
tutelage  in  which  she  was  kept  by  the  authority 
of  the  husband,  a  tutelage  which  was  sanctioned 
by  custom  and  law,  but  which  became  more  and 
more  branded  as  brutal  and  illegitimate.  Evolution 
of  the  family  thus  takes  place  in  the  direction  of 
the  decadence  of  authority  and  of  an  increase  of 
individual  liberty. 

Formerly  female  property  remained  indivisible, 
and  theoretically  at  least  belonged  to  the  family 
represented  by  the  ancestor  or  by  the  eldest  of 
the  children,  whose  duty  it  was  to  supply  the  needs 
of  all  the  other  members  of  the  family;  and  so 
property  became  more  and  more  individual.  In 
olden  times  certain  professions  were  hereditary,  and 
children  could  claim  public  support  by  taking  up,  in 
most  cases  under  compulsion,  a  profession  as  to 

1  La  Dissolution  opposee  cl  V Evolution,  p.  325. 


ANIMAL    SOCIETIES.  2O3 

which  they  were  allowed  no  choice;  but  in  our  day, 
children  are  almost  completely  independent  in  the 
choice  of  a  profession.  Woman  is  less  and  less  con- 
fined to  the  home;  she  takes  her  part  in  social  work, 
and  in  many  of  the  functions  of  public  life. 

93.  The  Future  of  the  Family. 

What,  then,  can  we  foresee  in  the  near  future  but  a 
still  more  complete  dissolution  of  the  family  and  a 
greater  homogeneity  of  all  its  elements,  the  pro- 
gressive disappearance  of  every  vestige  of  the  ancient 
patria  potestas  and  jus  marital et  a  more  and  more 
marked  independence  of  the  different  members, 
who  will  always  be  bound  by  legal,  economical,  and 
moral  ties  to  one  another,  but  who  will  be  fretted 
less  and  less  by  those  ties  in  their  civil  action  and 
in  the  exercise  of  their  aptitudes  ?  In  fact,  the  family 
solidarity  which  formerly  visited  upon  the  children 
the  sins  of  their  ancestors  to  the  thirtieth  generation, 
and  which  made  of  the  family  honour  so  powerful  a 
motive  to  minds  attached  to  tradition,  will  place 
an  ever-diminishing  obstacle  in  the  way  of  a  wider 
solidarity  and  the  formation  of  free  and  extended 
groups. 

94.  Animal  Societies. 

The  existence  of  a  social  organisation  among  the 
animals  inferior  to  man  has  been  proved  by  M. 
Espinas  in  his  excellent  treatise  on  animal  societies.1 
But  the  same  author  has  shown  the  diversity  of  the 
principles  of  common  life,  from  that  of  parasitism  to 
that  of  conjugal  society.  May  we  not  suppose  that 

1  See  also  Prince  Kropotkin,  Mtttual  Aidy  passim.  — TR. 


204  SOCIAL    EVOLUTION. 

human  societies  have  been  constituted  on  other 
foundations  than  those  of  "animal  societies"?  No 
doubt  there  is  a  continuity  in  the  evolution  of  the 
animal  kingdom,  and  the  stages  between  the  inferior 
and  the  human  modes  of  social  organisation  are 
marked  by  numerous  intermediaries.  But  there 
comes  a  time  when  moral  and  rational  considera- 
tions intervene,  when  society  is  judicially  constituted, 
when  organisation  from  being  spontaneous  becomes 
reflective,  when  beings  living  in  common  become 
conscious  of  their  aptitude  for  regular  collective 
action  and  of  the  requirements  of  that  mode  of 
life,  and  of  the  possibility  of  effecting  lasting  modi- 
fications therein  from  the  point  of  view  of  progress. 
Is  not  this  the  stage  when  organisation  becomes 
really  social  because  it  is  really  human  ? 

Some  authors  claim,  it  is  true,  that  there  is  already 
among  animals  a  kind  of  judicial  institution : l  a  solemn 
and  deliberate  sentence  to  death  with  all  the  char- 
acteristics of  a  judicial  execution,  according  to  Dr. 
Ballion. 

However,  the  ideas  of  right  and  justice,  of  law  and 
of  violation  of  law,  of  obligation,  of  acts  permitted  or 
forbidden,  can  only  proceed  from  moral  reflection, 
and  they  are  indispensable  in  the  conversion  into 
political  facts  of  such  facts  as  may  be  connected  with 
a  "pre-social"  phase — facts  of  reaction,  of  collective 
restraint,  and  of  life  in  common,  in  the  stage  where 
there  is  no  other  foundation  for  the  existence  of 
community,  but  imitation,  spontaneous  sympathy,  and 
what  M.  Durkheim  calls  "mechanical  solidarity."2 

1  Kropotkin,  op.  cit.,  p.  58.— TR. 

2  Spencer,  Principles  of  Psychology,  chap.  xvii.  5,  Sociality  and  Sym- 
pathy. — TK. 


THE    STRUGGLE   OF   CLASSES.  205 


95.  Political  Life  and  the  Struggle  of  Classes. 

When  the  observation  of  certain  rules  deliberately 
laid  down  is  required  for  the  accomplishment  of  acts 
hitherto  left  to  the  individual  choice,  when  law 
replaces  custom,  whatever  may  be  the  origin  of 
law  and  the  power  which  promulgates  it — provided 
that  there  arises  in  us  all  a  sense  of  obligation — when 
authority  is  established,  then  political  life  com- 
mences, and  then  only  can  there  be  a  question  of 
morality  or  immorality  in  the  State. 

Now  the  influence  of  "  authority  "  is  felt  from  an 
early  date  in  the  evolution  of  the  human  race.  We 
know  of  no  race,  no  tribe,  no  clan,  in  which  there 
does  not  exist  a  collective  will  expressed  by  verbal  or 
written  prescriptions  which  are  well  known  to  all, 
and  which  already  constitute  the  law.  The  form 
of  government  matters  relatively  little,  and,  as  with 
Plato  and  Aristotle,  too  much  importance  perhaps 
has  been  attached  to  the  sometimes  quite  superficial 
opposition  between  the  monarchical,  the  aristocratic, 
and  the  democratic  forms. 

What  matters  much  more  is  the  spirit  of  the 
government,  the  conception  of  the  relations  which 
are  to  be  created  or  maintained  between  the  State 
and  the  individual.  Is  there  any  correspondence 
between  the  State  and  the  nation  ?  Is  there  any 
opposition,  and  therefore  is  the  State,  that  is  to  say 
the  organ  of  coercion  and  of  government,  the  main- 
spring of  authority,  only  a  portion  of  the  nation, 
or  are  there  intermediaries  between  it  and  the 
people?  Do  these  intermediaries  consist  of  classes 
or  castes,  and  does  the  law  vary  according  to  the 


206  SOCIAL    EVOLUTION. 

caste  ?  That  is  the  important  point  to  consider  in 
social  evolution. 

It  seems  that  in  general  the  power  was  first  in  the 
hands  of  the  public,  who  showed  their  authority 
especially  in  reprisals  on  some  of  their  members 
for  outrage  against  public  feeling.  The  greater  the 
outrage,  the  more  it  attacked  deeply  rooted  senti- 
ments, the  more  violent  was  the  social  reaction,  and 
the  more  unity  was  there  in  the  exercise  of  collective 
power.  So  that,  as  M.  Durkheim  has  shown,  the 
law  was  to  all  intents  and  purposes  the  penal  law. 
Political,  religious,  economical,  and  family  organisa- 
tion for  a  long  time  formed  among  many  tribes  an 
indivisible  and  not  yet  differentiated  whole.  How 
could  distinct  classes,  the  one  dominant,  the 
other  subordinate,  be  constituted  and  give  rise 
to  those  political  struggles  which,  proceeding 
unchecked,  brought  about  an  accumulation  of 
injustice  and  crime — gave  rise  to  rivalries  and 
conquests,  and  caused  the  formation  of  distinct, 
and  in  most  cases  hostile  nationalities  ?  There  is 
no  doubt  that  the  increase  of  density  in  different 
populations  was  one  of  the  principal  causes  of  those 
great  political  and  military  movements  which  ended 
in  the  intermingling  of  different  races,  and  for  a  long 
time  secured  the  rule  of  the  strongest. 

The  formation  and  the  disappearance  of  castes  or 
distinct  classes  being,  as  we  have  seen,  the  most 
important  phenomenon  of  social  evolution,  one  sees 
in  succession  religious,  military,  and  plutocratic 
castes  predominant,  according  as  the  evolution  of 
a  country  is  more  or  less  advanced. 

But  the  rule  of  the  castes,  which  flourished  in 
antiquity  among  both  European  races  and  the 


THE    IDEA   OF   EQUALITY.  207 

Egyptians,  gradually  disappeared.  The  transient 
predominance  of  a  sect  has  replaced  the  constant 
supremacy  of  a  caste  in  communities  without  stable 
political  organisation,  such  as  the  Semitic  tribes  and 
the  Arabs.  In  modern  nations  "the  struggle  of  the 
classes "  seems  to  be  daily  on  the  decrease.  M. 
Lalande  rightly  points  out  "the  increasing  inter- 
relation of  men  to  one  another,  and  at  each  stage 
of  their  development  a  corresponding  assimilation 
of  aims,  ideas,  and  sentiments  which  were  at 
the  outset  opposed."  Homogeneity  proves  superior 
to  diversity  in  practice,  "tendencies  towards  unity 
urge  men  to  destroy  the  very  differences  that 
nature  gives  to  them  ready  made.  Every  external 
mark  of  specialisation  which  was  once  regarded 
with  pride  now  falls  into  discredit."  Everywhere 
in  the  family  as  in  the  State,  in  habits  as  in 
language,  the  assimilation  proceeds  apace;  common 
interests  unite  men  of  very  different  origin;  individuals 
of  every  social  sphere  are  constantly  being  brought 
into  closer  contact;  so  that  we  may  consider  the 
different  "  classes  "  of  society  as  superannuated  forms 
in  which  before  long  no  individual  will  care  to  find 
himself. 

96.  The  Idea  of  Equality.1 

M.  Bougie2  examines  and  explains  the  develop- 
ment in  modern  Western  society  of  the  idea  of 
equality,  which  was  part  of  the  social  conscious- 
ness of  the  ancients.  In  antiquity,  as  Fustel  de 
Coulanges  has  pointed  out,  "the  city  was  the  only 

1  Cf.  Mackenzie,  An  Introduction  to  Social  Philosophy,  pp.  249-286  ; 
Sorley,  op.  cit.,  pp.  69-73  >  Maine,  Ancient  Law,  pp.  92-96.  — TR, 

2  Les  Idkes  egalitaires.      Alcan,  1899. 


2C>8  SOCIAL    EVOLUTION. 

living  force;  there  was  nothing  above  it  and  nothing 
below  it."  It  was  only  at  the  close  of  the  Roman 
period,  under  the  influence  of  Stoicism  and 
Christianity,  that  the  individual  appears  as  an 
end  and  becomes  a  more  or  less  independent  centre, 
the  "point  of  intersection  of  very  numerous  and 
very  different  circles  which  compete  in  distinguish- 
ing his  personality  from  that  of  others."  The  idea 
I  of  equality  develops  in  proportion  as  density  of 
population,  social  mobility,  rapidity  and  frequency  of 
communication,  and  homogeneity  co-existing  with 
considerable  differentiation,  increase  in  a  nation  or 
a  totality  of  nations.  Societies  which  being  unified 
while  they  are  becoming  complex,  whose  units  are 
being  assimilated  at  the  same  time  that  they  are 
developing  points  of  difference,  and  which  are  being 
simultaneously  concentrated  and  multiplied,  must 
habituate  men's  minds  to  the  idea  of  equality. 

Now  such  conditions  are  realised  in  modern 
Western  societies.  We  can  therefore  foresee  that 
"  habits  of  mind  opposed  to  the  idea  of  freedom  will 
be  shattered,  both  by  the  assimilation  which  unites 
the  members  of  one  group  to  those  of  another,  and 
by  the  differentiation  which  throws  into  mutual 
opposition  the  members  of  another  group."  The 
struggle  of  classes,  the  predominance  of  one  caste 
over  another,  are  social  phenomena  which  must 
disappear. 

But  for  ideas  of  equality  to  triumph,  since  unity 
and  diversity  must  proceed  pari  passu,  an  increasing 
centralisation  of  the  directing  and  coercive  power 
is  necessary.  A  centralised  government  increases 
density  of  population,  establishes  uniformity,  and 
"  tends  to  oppose  every  kind  of  group,  both  compact 


GOVERNMENTS. 

and    exclusive,    which    divides    society    into  clearly 

distinct  sections."1     What  is  then  the  form  which, 

in    the    near  future,   government   will    take  in    the 
ordinary  process  of  evolution  ? 

97.  Governments.2 

M.  Coste,  after  an  exhaustive  examination  of 
historical  data,3  thinks  that,  from  the  political 
point  of  view,  the  succession  of  governments 
absolute  or  patriarchal,  military -religious,  adminis- 
trative, parliamentary,  representative  and  judicial,  is 
inevitable.  He  sees  in  this  evolution  a  progressive 
decrease  of  subjection,  a  continuous  progress  to- 
wards the  suppression  of  despotism  and  the 
effective  protection  of  the  law.  There  is  less 
servitude  under  a  military  government  than  under 
absolute  patriarchal  rule,  because  in  the  military 
state  we  undergo  discipline,  while  in  the  primitive 
social  forms  rule  was  despotic  (whether  the  rule 
of  the  community  or  of  the  individual).  There 
was  less  oppression  under  administrative  than 
under  military  rule;  less  check  to  individual  liberty 
under  representative  rule  than  under  administrative; 
and  finally,  under  judicial  rule,  "the  most  complete 
liberty  possible  involves  the  admissibility  of  all,  not 
only  to  public,  but  to  social  functions;  and  this 
must  end  in  a  given  time  in  bringing  together — a 
matter  of  the  utmost  advantage  to  society  and  the 
individual — the  task  which  is  to  be  performed, 

1  Bougie,  op.  cit. 

2  Mackenzie,  op.  cit.,  pp.  329  et  seq.     Proal,  Political  Crime,  pp.  173- 
205,  312-339.— TR. 

3  Ad.  Coste,  L?  Experience  des  Peuptes  et  les  Previsions  qitelk  aulorise, 
pp.  186-193.     Paris,  Alcan,  1900. 

14 


210  SOCIAL   EVOLUTION. 

and  the  man,  wherever  he  may  come  from,  who 
is  found  most  competent  to  perform  it."  And 
therefore  favouritism,  castes,  classes  in  an  attitude 
of  hostility,  checks  to  the  free  expansion  of  individual 
value,  and  opposition  between  the  State  and  the 
nation,  beyond  the  legal  opposition  of  the  govern- 
ment to  the  governed,  must  all  disappear.  This, 
then,  is  the  final  stage  of  an  evolution  which  has 
been  in  operation  for  ages. 

98.  Plutocracy. 

Mr.  Brooks  Adams,1  who  does  not  believe  so  much 
in  evolution  as  in  a  series  of  "  ricorsi "  such  as 
Vico  suggested,  throws  into  relief  the  preponderating 
power  of  money  in  political  evolution.  M.  Ad.  Coste 
recognises  that  "  trouble  is  almost  inevitable  between 
the  parliamentarian  system  (whether  monarchical  or 
republican  in  form)  and  plutocracy";  but  with  much 
optimism  he  foresees  that  in  the  not  remote  future 
the  power  of  parties  and  of  the  middle  classes,  and 
the  power  of  riches,  will  yield  to  the  pow^er  of  the 
intellect  and  of  free  association.  Mr.  Brooks  Adams 
seems  to  make  too  much  of  that  entity — the  race; 
he  feels  that  after  three  or  four  generations  exhausted 
blood  needs  purification  and  renewal  by  the  contact 
of  a  new  race,  lest  it  should  recommence  the  fatal 
cycle  which  begins  with  militarism  and  ends  in  an 
inevitable  decadence,  in  the  lowering  of  the  moral 
level  by  triumphant  plutocracy.  New  races  pene- 
trate but  slowly  into  the  great  current  on  which 
civilised  nations  are  borne;  the  elements  of  both 
mingle  very  slowly;  so  that,  properly  speaking,  there 

1  La  Loi  de  la  Civilisation  et  de  la  Decadence.     Alcan,  1899. 


POLITICAL    EVOLUTION    AND    LAW.  211 

is  no  race  which  is  just  entering  on  its  existence,  and 
no  race  just  coming  to  an  end.  And  further,  there 
are  no  two  "  races  "  or  groups  of  nations  which  have 
a  similar  evolution,  and  one  cannot  infer  from  the 
slow  decomposition  of  the  Byzantine  or  of  the 
Roman  world  the  inevitable  decadence  of  the 
European  civilisation  of  the  present  day.  In- 
dustrial development  will  probably  be  an  obstacle 
to  the  pernicious  influence  of  money.  No  doubt  it 
will  also  be  an  obstacle  to  the  incessant  struggle 
between  the  classes,  which,  in  the  eyes  of  a  German 
sociologist,  M.  Zenker,1  appears  inevitable  and  eter- 
nal. His  conception  of  the  State  as  a  hierarchy 
of  castes  maintained  in  subjection  by  the  brute 
power  of  another  caste,  which  is  but  temporarily 
predominant,  seems  to  proceed  from  an  incomplete 
view  of  social  evolution. 

The  idea  of  a  reign  of  law  and  right,  as  opposed 
to  a  reign  of  force  and  money,  has  made  incontest- 
able progress,  and  has  become  an  integral  part  of  the 
social  consciousness  of  civilised  races. 

99.  Political  Evolution  and  Law.- 

That  political  evolution  takes  place  in  the  direc- 
tion of  a  greater  independence  of  the  individual  ( 
with  respect  to  all  arbitrary  power  is  shown  by  the 
evolution  of  law.  As  we  saw  above,  law  was  first 
of  all  almost  entirely  penal.  The  harm  caused  to 
individuals  escaped  all  repression  when  it  constituted 
no  offence  to  collective  sentiment,  and  one  might 
quote  many  examples  of  crime  against  the  individual, 

1  Naturliche  Entwickelungsgeschichte  Gesdlschaft.     Berlin,  1899. 

2  Proal,  op.  «/.,  pp.  279-353;  Maine,*/.  cit.t  pp.  25,  113-151.— TR. 


212  SOCIAL    EVOLUTION. 

and  even  of  murders,  judged  much  less  severely  by 
primitive  societies  than  the  forgetting  of  a  ritual  pre- 
scription, which  seems  to  us  in  these  days  entirely 
insignificant.  There  is  therefore  in  primitive  law 
a  sure  indication  of  the  importance  assumed  by 
Authority,  and  of  the  small  value  attached  to 
persons  and  individual  rights.  It  may  be  said 
that  the  latter,  properly  speaking,  do  not  exist,  for 
the  individual  is  as  it  were  submerged  in  the  social 
mass.;  he  is  not  yet  sufficiently  disengaged  from  his 
environment  to  oppose  his  moral  force  to  the  brute 
force  of  the  community.  Certain  historians  of  the 
law  have  given  with  Fragapane  the  name  of 
"  pre-juridic  "  to  this  social  phase,  because  it  seems 
dominated  by  individual  or  collective  vengeance. 

The  vengeance  of  the  community  is  already  exer- 
cised, not  only  as  a  purely  impulsive  reaction,  but 
also  as  a  means  of  social  preservation,  of  the  pre- 
,  servation  of  traditions,  rites,  customs,  feelings,  and 
tendencies  which  afe  the  very  soul  of  common  life. 
It  is  the  "social  spirit,"  as  M.  Tanon1  says,  "which 
by  its  force  alone  creates  the  whole  of  law";  and 
it  can  only  be  so  in  nascent  societies,  in  which  simpli- 
city and  uniformity  of  the  conditions  of  life  and  culture 
impress  on  each  member  of  the  community  the  same 
manner  of  feeling  and  thinking,  and  make  each  em- 
brace and  conceive  uniform  views  of  the  whole  of 
moral  and  judicial  life.  Thus  there  is  really  law  in 
the  first  phase  of  social  life,  and  this  law  is  the 
point  at  which  the  evolution  we  have  to  examine 
begins.  This  penal  law,  founded  on  social  con- 
straint, allows  of  the  second  and  third  phases 
indicated  by  Fragapane :  the  "  arbitrary  legal 

1  Tanon,  V  Evolution  du  Droit,  p.  74.      Alcan,  1900. 


THE    LAW   OF   CONTRACT.  213 

phase,"  the  phase  of  vengeance  and  settlement ; 
and  the  "executive  legal  phase,"  that  of  the  im- 
perative intervention  of  authority  for  the  purpose 
of  a  coercive  sanction. 


100.  The  Law  of  Contract.1 

In  the  course  of  these  two  phases,  the  importance 
assumed  by  the  individual  becomes  greater  and 
greater.  The  law  of  contract  with  its  restitutive 
sanction  is  progressively  opposed  to  the  penal  law  ' 
with  its  purely  repressive  sanction.  Commercial 
customs,  the  development  of  relations  between 
races,  tribes,  and  nations,  must  ever  contribute  to 
the  expansion  of  this  law  which  makes  a  large 
number  of  practical  determinations  depend  on  a 
contract  freely  entered  upon,  and  no  longer  on  the 
arbitrary  will  of  the  sovereign. 

The  obligations  imposed  by  the  law  thus  became 
less  numerous  than  the  obligations  accepted  in 
consequence  of  an  agreement  between  individuals. 
The  civil  law  successfully  opposed  the  criminal 
law;  and  in  our  days  the  former  has  acquired  a 
preponderance  which  is  incontestable. 

In  fact,  the  simple  contract  between  individuals 
is  not  sufficient  to  constitute  a  legal  act.  There  is 
no  legal  fact  unless  the  assistance  of  public  authority 
is  assured  for  the  execution  of  the  contract.  For 
that  to  be  the  case,  the  contract  must  be  established 
in  the  forms,  under  the  conditions,  and  within  the 
limits  fixed  by  the  law.  Now  we  see  the  law 
penetrating  further  and  further  into  the  domain 
of  private  life  and  of  the  individual  will  for  the 

1  Maine,  Ancient  Law,  chap.  ix. — TR. 


214  SOCIAL    EVOLUTION. 

purpose  of  regulating  the  most  varied  modes  of 
action,  and  of  thus  giving  them  all  a  social  value 
and  a  legal  sanction.  While  formerly,  and  from  the 
beginning  of  evolution,  the  collective  power  deter- 
mined as  much  as  possible  the  "  substance "  of 
actions,  thus  annihilating  the  individual  will,  main- 
taining by  force  the  primitive  homogeneity,  wre  now 
see  authority  endeavouring  more  and  more  to  impose 
a  common  form  on  every  act ;  but,  while  giving  a 
legal  form,  we  see  it  further  and  further  refraining 
from  determining  the  substance  of  the  obligations, 
leaving  that  duty  to  the  individuals  who  are  freely 
binding  themselves  by  the  contract.  In  marriage  in 
France,  for  instance,  it  is  only  in  default  of  anterior 
conventions  that  the  law  imposes  a  well-defined  rule. 
And  so  the  social  life  penetrates  more  and  more  into 
the  individual  life,  but  social  constraint  is  ipso  facto 
exerted  less  and  less  on  the  individual  will,  and 
thus  the  development  of  the  liberty  of  the  citizen 
is  intimately  connected  with  the  development  of 
the  legal  system.  And  so  we  see  those  races 
which  advanced  in  civilisation,  granting  to  the 
State  powers  of  the  most  varied  order,  and  at  the 
same  time  giving  to  individual  liberty  the  maximum 
extension,  while,  on  the  other  hand,  oriental  races 
are  those  in  which  we  see  the  minimum  of  import- 
ance attached  to  the  social  functions  of  the  State, 
and  the  minimum  development  of  individual  liberty. 
The  future,  then,  really  belongs  to  the  individual  who, 
under  the  control  and  the  protection  of  the  State,  will 
become  more  and  more  independent  of  all  arbitrary 
authority. 


THE    PRIMITIVE    ECONOMIC    STATE.  215 

II, 

SOCIAL    EVOLUTION   (Continued), 

10 1.  The  Primitive  Economic  State. 

IT  has  been  recently  alleged  that  economic  pro- 
gress in  primitive  humanity  was  effected  as  the  life 
of  the  hunter  or  fisher  gave  place  to  the  nomadic 
life  of  the  shepherd,  and  eventually  to  that  of  the 
farmer.  But,  "  over  more  than  half  the  globe,"  says 
Dargun,1  "pastoral  life  has  not  been  the  stage  of 
transition  between  hunting  and  agriculture,  and  in 
consequence  the  inhabitants  of  many  countries  have 
never  known  the  regime  of  property  which  is  peculiar 
to  a  race  of  shepherds.  Among  them  we  must  in- 
clude those  of  America,  Australia,  and  Polynesia  on 
the  one  hand,  and  at  any  rate  the  greater  part  of 
those  of  Asia  and  Africa  on  the  other.  We  must 
therefore  cease  to  consider  the  three  traditional 
stages  as  necessarily  successive  in  human  progress. 
And  further,  all  the  pastoral  tribes  that  we  know  do 
engage  in  agriculture,  although  in  a  very  dilatory 
fashion.  Hordes  of  nomadic  shepherds  are,  taken  as 
a  whole,  more  civilised  than  many  tribes  which  are 
devoted  to  agriculture."  This  gives  us  grounds  for 
believing  that  a  pastoral  life  is  posterior  to  primi- 
tive agriculture.  These  are  views  which  are  now 
generally  accepted,  and  Grosse  distinguishes  in  each 
group  of  shepherds,  hunters,  or  farmers,  the  inferior 

1  L.   Dargun,  "  Ursprung  und  Entwickelungsgeschichte  des  Eigen- 
thums,"  Zeilschr.  f.   Vergl.  Rechtswiss,  v.,  1884. 


2l6  SOCIAL   EVOLUTION. 

and  the  superior,  in  order  to  mark  that  these  groups 
correspond  rather  to  different  types  of  existence  than 
to  degrees  of  the  same  evolution. 

1 02.  Economic  Evolution. 

Whether  they  be  shepherds,  hunters,  or  farmers, 
primitive  races  have  an  economic  activity  which  is 
but  slightly  complex.  It  is  only,  it  seems,  at  the 
superior  stage  of  primitive  agricultural  life  that 
exportation,  commerce,  or  exchange  with  near  or 
remote  tribes  make  their  appearance.  Division  of 
labour,  the  separation  of  trades,  and  the  artisan's  life 
do  not  come  till  later.  The  development  of  in- 
dustrial activity  is  therefore  more  characteristic  of 
a  high  civilisation  than  the  expansion  of  commer- 
cial life  and  the  importance  of  exchange,  although 
commerce  obviously  cannot  reach  a  high  degree  of 
development  except  paripassu  with  industrial  progress. 

M.  Coste1  divides  economic  evolution  into  five 
principal  periods: — 

1.  Patriarchal   production  or  the  joint-tenancy  of 
productive  activity;    absence  of  monetary  exchange, 
inalienable  real  property  (jus  utendi). 

2.  Separation  of  professions  and  trades,  domestic 
and  artisan  production,  local  commerce,  inalienable 
landed  property  (jus  abutendi). 

3.  Division  of  labour  and  the  use  of  natural  driving 
power    in    manufactures,    regulated    inter-provincial 
and    colonial    commerce,    capital    and    commercial 
property. 

4.  The   mechanisation   of  labour  and  the  use  of 
physico-chemical    motors    in    machinery    and    tran- 

1  Op.  ell.,  p.  336. 


DIVISION    OF    LABOUR.  217 

sport,  conventional  international  commerce,  personal 
property. 

5.  Creation  of  economic  organisms  by  combination 
for  public  action,  of  protection  by  union  of  co-opera- 
tive association  of  capital  and  interested  individual 
activity;  free  exchange;  co-operative  property  for 
workers  on  the  plus  value  of  the  productive  funds 
chargeable  to  them. 

103.  Division  of  Labour :l 

Economic  evolution  would  therefore  be  character- 
ised by  an  increase  of  production,  more  and  more 
active  exchange,  the  progressive  suppression  of  every 
cause  of  loss  (checks  to  free  labour,  administrative 
tyranny,  frauds,  crises,  artificial  regulations),  in  short 
by  an  increasing  intervention  of  the  community  and 
of  the  State  for  the  protection  of  individuals  and  the 
utilisation  of  their  aptitudes. 

The  main  effect  of  this  evolution  in  the  last  century 
was  the  introduction  of  machinery  with  its  power  a 
hundred  times  greater  than  that  of  man,  the  in- 
cessant improvements  which  place  in  the  hands  of 
the  workman  the  greatest  variety  of  tools,  thus 
involving  a  great  diversity  of  functions,  and  an  ever- 
increasing  division  of  labour.  We  can  scarcely 
foresee  how  far  machinery  will  transform  industry, 
and  therefore  modify  economic  life.  But  it  certainly 
seems  that  the  age  of  competition  between  indi- 
viduals will  very  soon  be  brought  to  an  end. 
"  Economic  individualism,"  says  M.  Coste,2  "  is 

1  Marshall,  Principles  of  Economics.,  vol.  i.  pp.  310-327,  339-356; 
ibid.,  Economics  of  Industry ',  pp.  49^  seq.  ;  Walker,  Political  Economy , 
pp.  58  et  seq.  — TR. 

-  Op.  cit.,  p.  342. 


2l8  SOCIAL    EVOLUTION. 

perfectly  sound  when  it  lays  stress  on  the  fruitfulness 
and  the  needfulness  of  personal  initiative,  but  there 
are  no  grounds  for  the  supposition  that  it  is  self- 
sufficient.  Sociology  must  show  that  economic 
progress  consists  in  the  better  and  better  concerted 
co-operation  of  public  action,  of  associated  capital 
and  individualised  labour  without  any  undue  as- 
sumption of  superiority  on  the  part  of  one  of  these 
elements  over  the  others."  The  powerless  and 
costly  nature  of  competition,  belauded  as  it  is  by 
orthodox  economists,  has  been  shown  in  the  course 
of  the  nineteenth  century.  It  has  caused  ruin  and 
failure  which  concerted  action  would  have  avoided. 
Division  of  labour,  specialisation  of  work,  and  there- 
fore of  aptitudes,  while  giving  increasing  value  to 
the  individual,  makes  more  and  more  urgent  the 
demand  for  co-operation,  and  for  the  solidarity  of  all 
the  factors  of  wealth,  and  of  all  the  elements  of 
economic  life.  M.  Durkheim  has  ably  shown  how 
"  organic  solidarity "  increases  with  the  division  of 
labour,  and  brings  in  its  train  an  increase  of  that 
individual  liberty  which,  in  spite  of  their  desire  to 
keep  it  intact,  the  supporters  of  competition  have  but 
indifferently  safeguarded.  The  division  of  labour 
and  solidarity  allow  of  an  indefinite  progress  of  the 
machinery  without  reason  for  fearing  the  conse- 
quences. Brute  force  in  man  will  become  of  less 
and  less  account ;  intellectual  power  and  technical 
skill  will  be  more  and  more  appreciated.  For  it 
cannot  be  maintained  that  a  machine,  however 
perfect  it  may  be,  will  be  directed  by  an  ignorant 
and  clumsy  workman  as  well  as  by  one  who  is 
skilful,  capable  of  performing  the  maximum  of 
useful  work,  and  of  repairing,  when  occasion  arises, 


ASSOCIATION. 


2IQ 


the  machinery  with  which  he  is  familiar,  and  which 
he  uses  with  the  more  precision  in  proportion  as  he 
is  familiar  with  it.  It  has  been  said  that  the  advent 
of  the  long-range  rifle  has  shown  that  valour  and 
courage  on  the  field  of  battle  are  useless;  but  it  has 
made  intelligence  far  more  valuable.  In  the  same 
way  machinery  makes  brute  force  of  ho  avail;  it 
makes  still  more  valuable  the  qualities  of  mind  that 
a  long  apprenticeship  and  constrained  discipline 
enable  a  man  to  acquire.  From  the  purely  socio- 
logical point  of  view  it  brings  together  workmen  on 
the  same  work — work  which  is  always  getting  more 
complex.  It  makes  of  the  great  shop,  of  the  great 
factory,  of  the  industrial  city,  a  more  and  more 
unified  whole.  It  radically  contrasts  the  trades  of 
to-day  and  their  unions  with  those  of  the  Middle 
Ages,  when  corporations  subjected  industrial  activity 
to  the  domination  of  a  few  narrow  and  immutable 
rules,  and  left  the  individual  no  right  to  initiative, 
and  no  means  of  acquiring  personal  value.1 

104.  Association.2' 

The  unions  of  the  present  day  tend,  it  is  said,3  to 
"  economic  sovereignty,"  that  is  to  say,  to  the  regula- 
tion of  prices,  salaries,  and  hours  of  work ;  and  these 
regulations  are  imposed  on  all  workmen  and  on  all 
concerned,  and  would  thus,  it  seems,  clearly  affect 
individual  liberty.  M.  Yves  Guyot  agrees  with  M. 
Paul  Boncour  in  foreseeing  an  increasing  tendency 

1  Brentano,  History  and  Development  of  Guilds,  pp.  \oietseq. — TR. 

-  Mackenzie,  op.  cit.  ;  Marshall,  Principles  of  Economics,  pp. 
433-434,  710-711.— TR. 

3  J.  P.  Boncour,  Le  Fedkralisme  econoniique.  Preface  by  M.  Wai- 
deck- Rousseau.  Alcan,  1900. 


220  SOCIAL    EVOLUTION. 

to  "socialistic  tyranny."  Nothing  is  more  natural 
to  a  mass  of  men,  suddenly  organised  into  powerful 
unions,  than  the  claim  to  exercise  an  unlimited  con- 
straint on  the  defenceless  individual.  The  instincts 
of  the  crowd  are  fundamentally  instincts  of  oppres- 
sion. We  have  seen  trade  unions  in  France  pursuing 
with  their  hatred  the  recalcitrant  among  their  fellows, 
and  the  only  reason  they  have  not  committed  illegal 
acts  is  that  justice  has  intervened. 

But  facts  such  as  these  are  rather  phenomena  of 
regression  than  of  evolution.  To  form  a  sane  judg- 
ment of  the  future  of  trade  unions  one  must  place 
oneself  above  all  that  is  accidental,  above  all 
unfortunate  incidents  and  transient  tendencies. 
Unbearable  tyranny  would  wreck  the  unions.  One 
may  therefore  predict  their  disappearance  within  a 
limited  period,  if  they  have  no  other  aptitudes  than 
those  which,  during  their  short  existence,  we  have 
been  enabled  to  discover. 

Happily  the  unions  have  other  reasons  for  their 
existence  than  the  tendency  of  the  mass  to  dominate 
and  oppress  the  individual.  Just  as,  from  the  politi- 
cal point  of  view,  evolution  has  taken  place  in  the 
direction  of  an  organisation  of  power,  so  that  the  law 
which  is  the  expression  of  reason  is  substituted  for 
the  individual  or  collective  choice — in  the  same  way 
from  the  economic  point  of  view  the  future  will  no 
doubt  show  a  more  or  less  rapid  transition  from 
"  socialistic  tyranny "  to  the  legal  liberty  of  the 
unions.  In  fact,  the  object  of  union  is  "  the  expres- 
sion of  professional  solidarity,"  and  the  putting  into 
practice  of  that  solidarity  which  during  past  cen- 
turies, and  notably  in  the  nineteenth  century,  has 
endeavoured  incessantly  to  manifest  itself  in  spite 


ASSOCIATION.  221 

of  obstacles  of  every  description  placed  in  the  way  of 
its  development  by  the  central  power.  There  is  a 
natural  grouping,  says  Mr.  Jay,1  "  which  arises  from 
community  of  residence,  and  another  which  is  derived 
from  community  of  occupation.  ...  In  both  cases 
special  relations  are  established,  similar  needs  are 
created,  competing  forces,  connections,  and  opposi- 
tions of  interest  arise  with  quite  a  body  of  relation- 
ships, the  co-ordination  of  which  into  a  regular 
regime  is  necessary  to  secure  safety  to  all,  and  to  each 
the  means  of  pursuing  his  ends" 

As  M.  Paul  Boncour  proves,  the  aspect  of  pro- 
fessional solidarity  varies  with  each  profession.  But 
it  exists  everywhere,  and  is  itself  a  justification  of  the 
existence  of  the  unions,  and  gives  the  surest  indica- 
tion of  the  future  of  economic  associations. 

Individual  liberty  does  not  therefore  seem  to  be 
threatened  by  the  organisation  of  collective  force. 
On  the  contrary,  indeed,  its  safety  would  be  best 
secured  by  the  unions  confining  themselves  to  a 
defence  of  their  common  rights  and  their  common 
independence.  Besides,  do  we  not  see  already  a 
tendency  to  substitute  for  the  violent  pressure  which 
is  sometimes  exercised  on  individuals  in  the  case  of  a 
strike,  a  kind  of  universal  suffrage,  a  referendum 
having  as  its  principle  the  free  expression  of  the  indi- 
vidual will,  and  as  its  end  the  methodic  establishment 
of  a  common  rule  ? 

M.  Paul  Boncour  foresees  a  yet  more  brilliant 
future  for  associations  of  every  kind,  and  in  particular 
for  the  trades  unions.  According  to  him,  the  day 
will  come  when  these  professional  groups  will  be 
invested  by  the  law  with  rights  similar  to  those  of 

1  Evohition  du  Regime  legal  du  Tr avail >  p.  16. 


222  SOCIAL    EVOLUTION. 

other  and  dissimilar  associations  (the  right  of  civil  or 
criminal  prosecution,  the  right  of  setting  in  motion 
public  action  in  the  case  of  misdemeanours  which 
come  within  their  competence) ;  when,  in  addition  to 
this  moralising  role,  they  will  give  valuable  assistance 
as  regards  laws  of  labour,  industry,  and  commerce,  to 
the  administration  of  those  laws,  and  to  the  political 
and  economic  organisation  of  the  country.  Federa- 
tion of  all  types  of  unions  might  serve  as  a  basis 
for  the  general  representation  of  the  interests  and 
tendencies  of  a  nation.1 

If  the  professional  unions  some  day  attain  such  a 
degree  of  co-ordination  and  of  political  or  legal 
weight,  entirely  new  conditions  of  equilibrium  of 
economic  forces,  and  in  particular  a  new  method 
of  division  of  wealth  among  the  workmen,  must  of 
necessity  come  into  force  in  each  country.2 

105.  Slavery  and  Property. 

The  division  of  property,  whether  natural  or 
acquired  by  labour,  was  for  a  long  time  effected 
according  to  principles  which  would  not  obtain  at 
the  present  day.  Almost  at  the  beginning  of  social 
evolution  we  find  slavery  depriving  certain  indi- 
viduals of  all  power  of  possession,  although  these 
very  individuals  were  the  only  workers  and  the  sole 
producers  of  wealth.3 

No  doubt  slavery  was  not  a  universal  fact  in 
humanity.  In  numerous  races  men  have  never  been 
enslaved  by  their  fellows;  and  if  Dr.  Nieboer  is  to  be 
believed,  and  his  treatise  is  full  of  evidence  on  this 

1  Paul  Boncour,  Le  Federalisme  economique,  pp.  354-377. 

2  Mackenzie,  op.  cif.,  pp.  323,  324.— TR. 

3  Maine,  Ancient  Law,  pp.  162  el  set/. — TR. 


SLAVERY  AND  PROPERTY.  223 

point,  military  races  have  been  much  less  prone  to 
institute  slavery  than  industrial  and  commercial 
communities;  but  we  may  consider  the  slavery  of 
individuals  or  of  entire  races  as  a  very  widely  spread 
"  industrial  system." 

The  process  has  been  very  general.  Everywhere 
we  see  that  when  economic  life  has  ceased  to  consist 
in  direct  exchange,  or  in  an  immediate  consumption 
of  natural  products,  whenever  industry  and  commerce 
have  been  developed,  there  then  appears  a  tendency 
on  the  part  of  the  stronger  to  oppress  the  weaker, 
'in  order  to  obtain  from  them  the  maximum  of 
labour  with  the  minimum  of  expense  or  pay. 

Now  this  tendency  gradually  disappears.  More 
and  more  must  there  ensue  an  exchange  of  services 
through  the  intermediary  of  money,  and  therefore  an 
accumulation  in  the  hands  of  the  greatest  number 
of  individuals  of  the  means  of  exchange  which 
constitute  private  property. 

Industrial  progress  has  freed  the  workman.  The 
increasing  complexity  of  the  means  of  production, 
multiplicity  of  inventions,  the  necessity  of  profiting 
by  every  natural  resource  in  regions  where  none  but 
hard-working  men  can  live,  have  made  division  of 
labour  inevitable.  The  difficulties  of  the  struggle 
for  existence  have  made  certain  races  bolder,  more 
ready  for  innovation,  and  more  inclined  to  appreciate 
skill,  the  spirit  of  invention,  and  technical  value. 
While  the  nations  which  lived  on  a  rich  soil,  in 
fertile  plains,  continued  to  live  without  effort,  and 
endeavoured  to  keep  a  considerable  number  of  slaves, 
the  races  which  lived  on  a  poor  soil,  in  mountainous 
districts,  put  forth  all  their  energies,  and  in  the 
accomplishment  of  their  common  tasks  accustomed 


224  SOCIAL    EVOLUTION. 

themselves  to  the  equality  of  all  before  the  law,  and 
conceived  the  idea  of  the  aptitude  of  all  to  possession 
in  general,  and  the  right  of  each  to  possess  the  fruits 
of  his  labour.  And  thus,  as  Spencer1  has  so  clearly 
shown,  industrialism  assisted  the  development  of 
individual  property.  And  besides,  as  the  English 
philosopher  points  out,  since  the  diversity  and  the 
importance  of  personal  property  possessed  by  in- 
dividuals increases  with  industrialism,  land  is  little 
by  little  assimilated  to  the  product  of  work,  and  is 
blended  with  primitive  personal  property,  so  that 
landed  property  is  also  subject  to  an  evolution  which 
tends  to  make  the  good  that  nature  brings  us  and 
all  kinds  of  natural  and  artificial  wealth  more  and 
more  strictly  individual. 

106.  Property. 

Nomadic  races  could  scarcely  conceive  of  any 
other  individual  property  than  that  of  weapons  and 
a  limited  number  of  movable  articles.  Warlike  races 
added  to  these  the  possession  of  booty;  agricultural 
races,  which  seem  the  most  apt  to  conceive  of  real 
property,  have  not,  as  a  rule,  admitted  at  the  outset 
that  a  part  of  the  common  soil  may  be  exclusively 
reserved  for  the  individual.  It  was  only  as  the  art 
of  agriculture  progressed  that  temporary  possession 
was  established.  "The  land,"  says  M.  de  Laveleye, 
"  continues  to  remain  the  collective  property  of  the 
clan,  to  which  it  returns  from  time  to  time  for  the 
purpose  of  redistribution.  This  is  the  system  in 
force  at  the  present  day  in  Russian  communities. 
In  the  time  of  Tacitus  it  was  the  system  among  the 
Germanic  tribes." 

1  Principles  of  Sociology,  chap,  xv.— TR. 


PROPERTY.  225 

According  to  M.  Kovalewsky,  primitive  agrarian 
communism  was  first  destroyed  by  the  increasing 
density  of  the  population,  and  afterwards  by  political 
institutions  such  as  the  feudal  system,  or  by  social 
events  such  as  the  triumph  of  the  middle  classes. 
The  truth  is  that  the  communism  of  savage  hordes 
has  never  been  anything  but  the  lack  of  individual 
property,  and  can  only  be  defined  negatively,  for,  as 
M.  Zenker1  remarks,  the  mind  of  early  man  is  not 
complex  enough  to  grasp  at  once  the  idea  of  col- 
lective possession.  It  was  in  the  absence  of  all 
possession  that  individual  property  was  established, 
so  that  it  had  not  to  struggle  against  a  rival  and 
anterior  collectivism. 

Strength,  skill  in  handling  arms  and  in  getting 
the  best  of  it  in  the  fight,  as  Spencer  claims,2  were 
at  the  outset  the  foundation  of  the  special  advan- 
tages given  to  certain  men,  and  these  advantages 
degenerated  into  landed  property. 

In  proportion  as  technical  skill  and  intellectual 
or  moral  worth  acquired  a  wider  scope,  and  became 
the  rivals  in  public  estimation  of  warlike  reputation, 
private  property  became  more  widely  extended 
among  those  races  which  began  with  the  military 
regime.  In  other  cases,  the  bringing  into  relation 
of  the  soil,  mines,  quarries,  etc.,  by  means  of  labour 
has  allowed  of  more  or  less  lasting  usurpation.3 

But  we  must  be  careful  to  remember  that  the 
evolution  of  landed  property  had  to  pass  through 
a  stage  which  is  peculiar  to  it,  possession  by  the 
family  rather  than  by  the  individual.  In  our  days, 

1  Die  Geselhchaft,  vol.  i.  p.  80.  2  Op.  cit.,  chap,  xv.— TR. 

3  Thus  the  existing  law  of  property  sprang  in  1789  from  the  law  of 
property  which  obtained  in  the  Middle  Ages. 


226  SOCIAL    EVOLUTION. 

among  the  most  civilised  races,  there  still  remain 
unmistakable  traces  of  the  possession  of  real  pro- 
perty by  the  community  to  which  the  individual  is 
immediately  attached. 

When  it  is  not  the  family,  it  is  the  congregation 
or  the  group  that  is  charged  with  the  duty  of  safe- 
guarding the  community  of  joint-possession.  This 
:is,  properly  speaking,  the  collectivist  phase  of  social 
.evolution.  It  is  not  the  first  phase,  nor  is  it  the 
most  recent ;  it  is  intermediary  between  the  un- 
conscious communism  of  the  beginning,  and  the 
individualism  of  the  present  day.1 

Property  therefore  tends  to  become  more  and 
more  personal,  and  this  tendency  is  due  in  particular 
to  the  present  conditions  of  labour.  It  always  seems 
that  individualism  is  not  here  antagonistic  to  a  kind 
of  collective  possession,  possession  by  unions  or 
associations  of  different  kinds,  or  by  all  the  groups 
which  have  as  their  end  the  work  that  is  common 
to  different  individuals.  Individual  property  has 
nothing  to  fear  from  the  development  of  such 
collective  property,  which  is  perhaps  the  form  of 
possession  which  the  greatest  and  economically  the 
most  successful  enterprises  will  assume  in  the  future. 

107.  Capital  and  Labour? 

Industrialism  has  not  only  favoured  the  establish- 
ment of  individual  property;  by  the  accumulation 
of  capital  necessitated  by  great  industrial  enter- 

1  Even  under  the  feudal  system  we  find  family  "  tenure  "  generally 
preferred  to  individual  tenure.     Cf.  H.   Se"e,  Les  Classes  rurales  et  le 
Regime  domanial  en  France  au  moyen  Age,  1901. 

2  Marx,  Capital,  vol.  ii.  chap.  xv. ;  Thorold  Rogers,   The  Economic 
Interpretations  of  History  >  pp.  23,  228. — TR. 


CAPITAL   AND    LABOUR.  227 

prises,  it  has  also  given  rise  to  a  conflict  between 
capital  and  labour.  The  problem  of  the  fair  relation 
to  be  established  between  the  revenue  of  the  capi- 
talist and  the  earnings  of  the  worker  is  essentially 
modern,  one  may  even  say,  recent.  For  it  only 
came  into  being  when  the  variety  and  the  power 
of  machinery  had  modified  so  profoundly  the  tout 
ensemble  of  the  economic  phenomena  of  produc- 
tion.1 

The  suppression  of  ancient  corporations,  while 
destroying  many  abuses  and  unjustifiable  privileges, 
has  disorganised  those  workmen  to  whom  the  right 
of  association,  coalition,  and  co-operation  has  been 
for  a  long  time  denied.  Capital  has  turned  out  to 
be  omnipotent  in  the  face  of  defenceless  labour.  It 
has  been  followed  by  indisputable  abuses,  and 
enormous  fortunes  have  been  realised  by  capitalists 
who  certainly  had  less  right  than  their  workmen  to 
possess  profits  which,  after  all,  are  really  common. 

But  a  well-marked  evolution  tends  to  give  more 
and  more  solidarity  to  capital  and  labour.  The 
sharing  by  the  workmen  of  profits,  and  co-operation 
in  every  form,  seem  little  by  little  to  be  making  of 
each  labourer  a  small  capitalist  interested  both  in 
the  rise  of  wages  and  the  increase  of  dividends.2 

We  may  foresee  that  unions  will  assume  such 
dimensions  that  the  struggle  between  the  represen- 
tatives of  capital  and  labour  will  be  regulated  in  a 
manner  which  will  tend  to  become  more  and  more 
pacific,  when  we  take  into  consideration  the  re- 
spective strength  of  the  two  parties.3 

1  Marx,  op.  «?.,  chaps,  xxxi.,  xxxii. — TR. 

2  Marshall,  Principles  of  Economics,  pp.  366-368. — TR, 

3  Mackenzie,  op.  cit.,  p.  324. — TR. 


228  SOCIAL   EVOLUTION. 


1 08.  Collective  Sentiments. 

As  has  been  already  pointed  out  on  many  occasions, 
the  first  sentiments  which  developed  in  humanity 
took  in  general  a  religious  form ;  and  in  most  cases 
to  these  were  added  before  a  long  period  had  elapsed 
the  aesthetic  sentiments,  the  development  of  which 
was  encouraged  by  the  festivals,  the  games,  and  the 
ceremonies  that  have  always  been  held  in  honour 
among  all  races. 

Given  the  social  homogeneity  already  indicated, 
it  is  not  surprising  that  common  sentiments  have 
had  an  incomparable  degree  of  vivacity  and  energy, 
have  united  consciousnesses,  and  given  to  collective 
manifestations  their  practically  unanimous  support. 
Fanaticism  with  its  explosions  of  hatred  against 
heterodoxy  was  the  consequence.  And  as  the  social 
sentiments  make  but  one  whole  with  the  religious 
sentiments,  we  can  imagine  the  power  of  the  priests 
associated  with  that  of  the  chiefs,  or  that  of  the  chiefs, 
the  magistrates,  and  patriarchs,  who  were  invested 
with  a  religious  character.  The  morals  established 
by  religious  authority,  or  sanctioned  by  it,  could  not 
fail  to  be  perpetuated.  The  faithful  observation  of 
ethico-religious  prescriptions  assured  in  addition  the 
welfare  of  the  race,  thanks  to  the  fundamental 
hygienic,  moral,  or  political  character  of  those 
precepts,  stamped  as  they  often  were  with  the 
marks  of  great  prudence  and  lofty  wisdom.  The 
worship  of  the  totem,  respect  for  objects  tabooed, 
have  had,  and  we  cannot  ignore  the  fact,  a  useful 
purpose  in  general  civilisation.1 

1  Lang,  Custom  and  Myth,  pp.  245-304;  Letourneau,  op.  cit.^ 
pp.  273-275  ;  Chamberlain,  op.  cit.,  pp.  309  et  seq. — TR. 


PRIMITIVE    SENTIMENTS. 

To  the  vivacity  of  the  social-religious  sentiments 
was  due  the  profundity  of  the  aesthetic  sentiments, 
which,  at  the  outset,  in  the  case  for  instance  of  the 
Hindoo,  Egyptian,  Greek,  and  Christian  civilisations, 
were  affirmed  in  so  imposing  a  fashion. 

109.  Differentiation  of  the  Primitive  Sentiments. 

The  dissolution  of  the  primitive  religious  sentiment 
broke  the  bond  which  united  theology,  with  all  its 
paraphernalia  of  magic,  sorcery,  astrology,  and 
medicine,  to  politics,  art,  and  science. 

The  history  of  the  development  of  the  artistic  and 
scientific  sentiments,  is  that  of  universal  civilisation, 
often  interrupted,  and  often  resumed  by  the  different 
races  which  have  successively  taken  their  place  at  the 
head  of  humanity.  It  is  easily  proved  that  religious 
fanaticism  disappears  progressively  in  proportion  as 
a  race  advances  in  the  way  of  civilisation ;  that  the 
art  of  that  race  ceases  to  aim  at  the  sublime,  and 
becomes  more  attached  to  beauty  and  grace;  and 
that  the  love  of  science  and  the  worship  of  truth 
increase  at  the  same  time  as  the  sentiments  of 
sociability. 

The  development  of  the  scientific  tendencies  and 
of  sociability  characterises  our  own  age.  We  may 
therefore  foresee  a  progressive  diminution  of  politico- 
religious  hatred,  which  is  simply  a  survival  of  time 
past ;  a  new  orientation  of  art,  saturated  with 
generous,  altruistic,  and  social  sentiments,  and  a 
considerable  extension  of  the  domain  of  knowledge, 
as  well  as  of  the  sphere  of  social  work,  institutions 
of  solidarity,  of  mutuality,  of  political  organisation, 
etc. 


230  SOCIAL   EVOLUTION. 

no.  The  Evolution  of  Sociability.1 
Although  the  term  "sociability"  adequately  in- 
dicates an  individual  tendency,  it  is  too  vague  to 
indicate  the  complex  factor  which  seems  called  upon 
to  play  a  preponderant  part  in  the  near  future.  For 
an  accurate  conception  of  the  idea  we  must  consider 
its  evolution. 

The  constraint  exercised  in  primitive  times  by  the 
"social  conscience"  on  the  individual  conscience,  is 
not  only  shown  by  obedience  to  chiefs,  to  priests, 
and  to  political  power,  but  also,  as  we  have  seen,  by 
the  constant  disposition  of  all  individuals  to  submit 
themselves  to  a  common  rule,  to  adopt  the  morals, 
the  fashions  of  thought,  speech,  and  action  which 
custom  and  tradition  have  determined.  It  is  also 
this  constant  and  natural  disposition  which  made 
from  the  outset  the  power  of  the  collective  will  so 
great.  It  may  be  explained  by  a  kind  of  instinctive 
sympathy  or  spontaneous  imitation,  which  by  its 
promptitude  of  diffusion  very  quickly  gives  necessity 
and  generality  to  a  fashion,  a  custom,  or  a  social 
type.  Such  an  aptitude  is  the  point  of  departure 
of  sociability. 

But  when  the  power  of  collectivity  appears  to  the 
individual  already  considerably  weakened,  a  new 
kind  of  social  sentiment  must  necessarily  make  its 
appearance.  The  individual  is  adapted  for  life  with 
his  fellows,  no  longer  by  a  restraint  of  which  he 
is  unconscious,  but  by  the  development  of  a  generous 
tendency  which  is  favoured  by  life  with  weaker  beings. 
In  the  absence  of  this  tendency,  the  division  of  social 

1  Spencer,  Principles  of  Psychology,  Corollaries,  V. ;  Principles  of 
Sociology t  chap.  vi. — TR. 


EVOLUTION    OF   SOCIABILITY.  231 

labour,  as  M.  Durkheim  has  shown,  tends  to  substi- 
tute progressively  for  the  "mechanical  solidarity" 
of  the  first  stage,  an  "organic  solidarity,"  that  of 
conscious  elements  which  are  mutually  complement- 
ary, and  have  a  clearer  and  clearer  notion  of  the 
services  they  render,  and  of  the  services  that  are 
rendered  to  them ;  such  that  they  cannot  live  without 
the  help  of  others,  although  they  are  conscious  that 
they  are  rendering  to  others  valuable  services;  such 
that  they  cannot  develop  and  be  happy  unless  their 
environment  is  in  process  of  development,  and  in 
possession  of  relative  happiness. 

Industrial  progress,  closely  connected  with  scientific 
progress,  can  therefore  only  develop  a  new  sociability 
near  akin  to  the  sentiment  of  fraternity  and  the  spirit 
of  sacrifice. 

As  Spencer  pointed  out,1  for  sympathy  to  attain 
its  full  development  in  the  human  race,  the  keen- 
ness of  the  struggle  for  existence  must  decrease, 
first  between  individuals,  next  between  restricted 
communities,  and  finally  between  nations  and  races. 
Now  the  most  complete  adaptation  of  men  to  the 
conditions  of  existence  imposed  upon  them  by  nature 
and  social  evolution  gradually  eliminates  the  causes 
of  strife.  The  extension  of  means  of  communication, 
the  incessant  mingling  of  different  kinds  of  collec- 
tivities, the  necessity  for  numerous  and  different 
associations,  the  co-operation  which  is  imposed  on 
every  domain  of  activity,  bring  natural  sympathy 
every  day  into  contact  with  fewer  obstacles,  and 
enable  a  generosity,  which  at  first  is  feeble 
and  intermittent,  to  affirm  itself  with  increasing 
energy. 

1  Principles  of  Psychology,  Coroll.  V.,  conclusion. — TR. 


232  SOCIAL   EVOLUTION. 


in.  The  Religion  of  Humanity  and  of  the  Unknowable. 

Can  we  believe  in  the  near  approach  of  a  religion 
of  humanity  as  a  substitute,  according  to  Comte,  for 
every  form  of  worship  of  the  invisible  divinity  ?  Will 
human  fraternity  ever  become  equivalent  to  a  religious 
sentiment  ?  Spencer  foresees  a  development  of  this 
lofty  sentiment  which  will  no  longer  permit  us  to 
attribute  to  the  divinity  low  or  vicious  tendencies, 
and  an  intellectual  development  such  that  the  clumsy 
theological  explanations  that  have  been  formerly 
accepted  without  a  murmur  will  no  longer  be  accepted 
by  any  one,  and  therefore  he  forsees  a  purification  of 
religious  conceptions  rejecting  the  anthropomorphic 
characteristics  attributed  from  the  very  first  to  the 
Supreme  Being.  But  Spencer  is  far  from  supposing 
that  a  confusion  is  possible  of  the  Supreme  Being 
with  the  "  Great  Being,  Humanity."  He  believes 
that  in  the  most  primitive  religion  there  was  already 
a  part  of  truth,  to  wit,  that  "the  power  which 
manifests  itself  in  consciousness  is  but  a  differently 
conditioned  form  of  the  power  which  manifests  itself 
beyond  consciousness."1  The  mysterious  force,  the 
Unknowable,  would  thus  be  the  God  of  the  future, 
agnosticism  would  be  the  religion  of  the  future, 
the  product  of  the  intellectual  development,  and 
of  the  evolution  of  sentiments. 

"Those  who  think  that  science  is  dissipating 
religious  beliefs  and  sentiments  seem  unaware  that 
whatever  of  mystery  is  taken  from  the  old  inter- 
pretation is  added  to  the  new.  Or  rather,  we  may 

1  Howard  Collins,  "  Summary  of  Spencer's  Philosophy,"  Principles 
of  Sociology,  p.  511. — TR. 


SOCIOLOGICAL   ANTICIPATIONS.  233 

say  that  transference  from  the  one  to  the  other  is 
accompanied  by  increase,  since,  for  an  explanation 
which  has  a  seeming  feasibility,  science  substitutes  an 
explanation  which,  carrying  us  back  only  a  certain 
distance,  there  leaves  us  in  the  presence  of  the 
avowedly  inexplicable."1 

Spencer  takes  but  small  account  of  the  evolution 
of  the  social  sentiments  and  of  their  influence  on 
the  religious  conceptions  of  the  greatest  number. 
M.  Fouillee  would  seem  to  foresee,  and  rightly,  the 
approaching  predominance  of  altruistic  tendencies, 
and  of  a  spirit  of  social  reform,  of  a  kind  of  perhaps 
rather  mystical  philanthropy,  in  the  religion  which 
is  destined  to  attract  the  favour  of  the  multitude. 
Without  going  so  far  as  to  suppose  that  people  will 
make  of  Humanity  their  God,  Humanity  being  either 
far  too  abstract  to  be  clearly  conceived,  or  far  too 
concrete  to  be  idealised  and  to  respond  to  the  un- 
ceasing craving  for  the  -mysterious,  we  may  admit 
that  religion  will  become  more  and  more  impregnated 
with  sociability,  and  that  the  considerable  influence 
represented  by  ecclesiastical  authority  will  be  placed 
more  and  more  at  the  service  of  concord  and  social 
peace.2 


112.  Sociological  Anticipations. 

We  have  separately  examined  the  data  of  sociology 
as  to  the  past  evolution  of  the  principal  organs  of 
social  life,  and  we  have  thus  indicated  briefly  the 
foundations  of  sociological  anticipation  of  which 
we  must  now  gather  together  the  essential  features. 

1  Howard  Collins,  loc.  cit.,  p.  512.—  TR. 

2  Vide  Mackenzie,  Social  Philosophy,  pp.  324-327.— TR. 


234  SOCIAL   EVOLUTION. 

Thus  we  may  form  a  conception  as  objective 
as  possible  of  the  condition  and  the  tendencies 
of  that  society  in  the  midst  of  which  we  live  and 
act,  as  far  as  we  can,  in  harmony  with  our  environ- 
ment. 

1.  The  evolution  of  the  family  tends  to  the   dis- 
appearance of  the  arbitrary  power  of  the  father  and 
husband;  the  family  ceases  to  be  a  rigorously  close 
community,  its   elements  are  dispersed  and  acquire 
more  independence,  both  from  the  mechanical  and 
from  the  judicial  points  of  view. 

2.  The   evolution    of    political    life   tends   to   the 
suppression  of  caste,  of  oppressive  hierarchies,  and 
illegal  constraints;  authority  becomes  organised,  the 
conflict  of  classes  lessens,  and  ideas  of  equality  are 
propagated ;  the  law  of  contract  takes  precedence  of 
the  criminal  law,  and  distributive  of  repressive  justice; 
the  governmental  function  becomes  more  and  more 
a    magistracy,    which    exercises    its    action    in    all 
directions   in   order    to    prevent    injustice    and   the 
abuse    of    power    which    is    too    often    committed 
by   restricted   communities.      The    State    tends    to 
increase  the  extent  of  its   rights  and  its  functions, 
and  at  the  same  time  accords  to  the  individual  more 
liberty. 

3.  Economic  evolution  takes  place  in  the  direction 
of  the  free  association  of  workers  and  their  grouping 
into  more  and  more  powerful  unions.     Division  of 
labour  increases  the  industrial  power  of  humanity; 
it  frees  the  individual  by  giving  him  technical  worth, 
and  by  assuring  him  a  share  of  the  property  that  is 
the  result  of  his  work. 

4.  The  evolution  of  sentiment  is  effected  by  the 
transition  from  political  or  religious  fanaticism  to  a 


INDIVIDUALISM   AND   ALTRUISM.  235 

more  informed  and  salutary  sociability,  thanks  to  the 
progress  of  science,  which,  as  it  spreads,  develops 
more  and  more  the  love  of  truth. 

Can  we,  then,  give  a  synthetic  unity  to  these 
multiple  tendencies  ?  Can  they  co-exist,  and  if  so, 
how  far?  This  is  what  we  have  now  to  inquire; 
for  the  conception  of  the  social  Ideal  cannot  be 
arbitrary,  it  cannot  be  far  from  reality,  and  from 
what  we  foresee  it  can  only  be  realised  as  complete 
co-ordination  is  attained. 

Let  us  notice  in  the  first  place  that  a  general 
tendency  emerges  very  clearly  from  our  separate 
inquiries;  social  evolution  in  its  totality  tends  to 
make  of  the  most  civilised  man  a  being  more  and 
more  free,  under  the  control  and  the  protection  of 
an  authority  organised  to  support  the  reign  of  law 
by  suppressing  all  despotism ;  it  also  tends  with  the 
help  of  his  fellows  associated  with  him  in  different 
groups  to  make  him  realise  the  greatest  solidarity, 
and  to  develop  the  highest  social  sentiments.  Does 
not  this  tendency  furnish  us  with  the  direct  principle 
of  a  rational  construction  of  the  social  Ideal  ?  Are 
not  individual  liberty  and  solidarity  two  relatively 
antithetic  terms  that  we  have  now  to  reconcile  ? 


III. 

THE  SOCIAL  IDEAL. 

113.  Individualism  and  Altruism. 

SOME  contemporary  moralists  exalt  the  individual 
to  the  extent  of  forgetting  society,  and  others 
preach  a  love  of  man  which  is  equivalent  to  in- 


236  THE    SOCIAL   IDEAL. 

dividual  renunciation.  On  the  one  hand,  extreme 
individualism  issues  in  social  and  moral  anarchy;  on 
the  other,  an  exaggerated  altruism  arrives  at  con- 
clusions which  are  equally  fatal  to  social  life.  It 
will  suffice  to  contrast  two  moral  theories  equally 
in  favour  with  the  literary  public  of  our  own  time. 
They  are,  perhaps,  unequal  in  scope,  and  their 
success  may  well  be  ephemeral,  but  at  least  they  are 
worth  taking  as  examples,  representing  as  they  do 
two  tendencies  which  the  moralists  must  some  day 
take  into  account — the  theory  of  Nietzsche  and  the 
theory  of  Tolstoi.  Nietzsche  is  the  apostle  of  strife, 
of  force,  and  individual  greatness.  Tolstoi  is  the 
apostle  of  love,  peace,  gentleness,  and  humanity. 

114.  The  Over-man.1 

The  basis  of  Nietzsche's  doctrine  is  the  conception 
of  the  Uebermensch,2  a  product  of  this  life,  which 
without  an  evolution  towards  a  determinate  end  must 
always  "  be  surpassing  itself,"  and  which  only  offers 
peace  to  mortals  as  a  "  means  to  further  warfare."  To 
Nietzsche,  war  is  an  instrument  of  progress,  just  as 
to  Darwin  the  struggle  for  life  was  the  principle  of  the 
perfection  of  species.  War  ends  in  the  elimination 
of  the  less  fit,  and  in  the  advancement  of  the  victori- 
ous to  the  dignity  of  Uebermensch,  created  to  lead  a 
flock  of  slaves,  to  give  direction  to  life,  to  establish 
a  scale  of  values,  a  hierarchy  of  property.  "  The 
true  philosopher,"  says  M.  Lichtenberger,  "  is  the 

1  Vide  Fouillee,  "  The  Ethics  of  Nietzsche  and  Guyau,"  International 
Jotirnal  of  Ethics,  October  1902,  pp.    13-27;   Maurice  Adams,    *'The 

Ethics  of  Tolstoi  and  Nietzsche,"  op.  cit. ,  October  1900,  pp.  82- 106.  — TR. 

2  "  Over-man."— TR. 


THE    OVER-MAN.  237 

genial  poet  in  whose  mind  is  formulated  the  table  of 
values  in  which  each  man  of  a  given  epoch  believes, 
and  which  therefore  determines  all  his  acts.  ...  His 
vision  is  nothing  but  the  supreme  law  which  receives 
its  impulse  from  past  generations.  .  .  .  He  creates 
in  complete  freedom  and  independence,  careless  of 
good  or  evil,  of  truth  or  error;  he  creates  his  truth,  he 
creates  his  morality."1 

"  I  teach  to  you  the  Uebermensch"  said  Zarathustra 
to  the  assembled  people.  "  Man  is  something  which 
must  be  surpassed.  .  .  .  The  Uebermensch  is  the 
raison  d'etre  of  the  world." 

With  this  conception  of  a  moral  ideal  is  connected 
that  of  a  whole  social  system.  The  masters,  the 
creators  of  values,  play  on  the  earth  the  role  of 
supreme  legislators,  of  gods;  thereby  they  assure 
the  happiness  of  their  slaves,  who  are  but  moderately 
intelligent  beings  without  a  will,  vowed  to  obedience, 
who  must  have  a  secure  existence  free  from  responsi- 
bility and  care,  who  are  quasi-animal  in  their  humble 
self-contentment  (born  of  the  illusion  that  there  is  an 
order  of  things  in  which  they  are  playing  a  useful 
part).  Between  the  masters  and  the  slaves  are  the 
warriors,  the  guardians  of  the  law,  governors,  kings, 
organs  of  transmission  whose  duty  it  is  to  carry  out 
the  wishes  of  their  masters,  the  real  rulers.  The 
hero,  the  sole  sovereign,  the  master,  is  not  happy :  his 
duty  is  to  ensure  the  happiness  of  inferior  beings,  and 
he  must  attain  the  supreme  degree  of  pain.  He  must 
therefore  "endeavour  to  bring  into  contact  at  the  same 
time  his  supreme  pain  and  supreme  hope."  Pessi- 
mism and  melancholy  cannot  abate  his  courage; 
"he  ought  on  the  contrary  to  learn  divine  laughter, 

1  La  Philosophic  de  Nietzsche  (4th  edit.),  pp.  152-153.     Alcan,  1900. 


238  THE    SOCIAL   IDEAL. 

and  try  to  surpass  himself  in  laughter  and  in  the  dance. 
That  is  the  supreme  advice  of  Zarathustra."  l 

This  fantastic  being  who  "sanctifies  laughter" 
experiences  neither  remorse  nor  pity.  :'  This  is  the 
new  law,  brethren,  that  I  give  you:  be  pitiless." 
Pity  is  the  last  sin  to  which  Zarathustra  is  tempted. 
But  while  the  God  of  the  Christians  died  in  his 
wish  to  sound  the  wicked  depths  of  the  human  soul, 
and  while  he  suffered  from  the  shameful  vices  of 
his  fellows,  the  God  of  Nietzsche  has  assured  his 
triumph  by  respecting  great  misfortune  and  ugliness, 
and  sparing  it  his  pity. 


115.  Sacrifice  oj  the  Unfit. 

"  To  spare  future  generations  the  depressing  spec- 
tacle of  poverty  and  ugliness,  let  what  is  ripe  for 
death  die ;  let  us  have  the  courage  not  to  help  those 
who  fall,  but  to  push  them  farther,  so  that  they  may 
fall  the  quicker.  The  sage  ought  not  only  to  be  able 
to  bear  the  sight  of  the  sufferings  of  others,  but  he 
ought  to  make  them  suffer  without  troubling  his 
head  with  the  idea  of  the  tortures  to  which  they 
are  subjected.  .  .  .  Who  would  attain  greatness  if 
he  did  not  feel  the  power  and  the  will  to  inflict 
great  suffering  ?  " 

The  naturalistic  idea  of  the  struggle  for  existence 
has  never  been  more  vigorously  pushed  to  its  ex- 
treme consequences.  No  doubt  Spencer  had  sketched 
the  process  of  "all  those  agents  who,  undertaking  to 
protect  the  incapable  taken  as  a  whole,  do  incontest- 
able harm,  for  they  check  the  work  of  natural 

1  Lichtenberger,  op.  cit.y  p.  159. 


SACRIFICE    OF   THE    UNFIT.  239 

:  elimination  by  which  society  is  continually  purged."1 
But  Spencer  had  admitted  the  good  effect  of  indi- 
vidual altruism;  he  did  not  imagine,  as  did  Nietzsche, 
an  elite  charged  with  the  duty  of  annihilating  as 
rapidly  as  possible  the  mass  of  unfortunates  who 
are  made  unfit  for  the  struggle  for  existence  by 
their  incurable  infirmities  or  their  natural  weakness. 

No  doubt  the  ferocity  of  the  master,  the  disciple 
of  Zarathustra,  is  simply  frightful  to  our  moral  con- 
science, fashioned,  it  is  true,  by  several  centuries  of 
that  Christianity  which  Nietzsche  abhors.  Our 
hearts  are  weakened,  and  we  have  spent  ourselves  for 
a  "morality  of  slaves."  Under  the  pompous  name 
of  "the  religion  of  human  suffering"  would  be 
hidden  on  the  one  hand  a  decrease  of  vitality,  an 
"ignominious  mediocrity,"  and  on  the  other  hand 
the  desire  to  give  oneself  an  easy  triumph  through 
the  sentiment  of  pity. 

"  We  do  good  to  others  just  as  we  do  ill  to  them, 
simply  to  give  ourselves  the  feeling  of  power,  and 
to  submit  them  in  a  measure  to  our  domination. 
The  strong  man  of  noble  instincts  seeks  his  equal  to 
struggle  with  him.  .  .  .  The  weak  on  the  contrary 
will  be  content  with  inferior  prey.  The  pitiful  man  is 
sure  to  meet  with  the  minimum  of  resistance,  and  to 
reap  a  success  with  the  minimum  of  danger  to  him- 
self." 2  And  so,  in  the  mind  of  Nietzsche,  pity  covers 
with  a  deceitful  veil  both  pride  and  the  selfishness  of 
an  inferior  being  without  a  spark  of  generosity.  Pity 
appears  to  him,  as  it  did  to  Spinoza,  a  depress- 
ing passion,  which,  by  adding  to  the  evils  which 

1  Vide   "The   Sins   of  Legislators"   in    The   Man    v.     The   Slate, 
passim;  Ritchie,  Darwinism  and  Politics,  pp.  28  et  seq. — TR. 

2  Cf.  Lichtenberger,  op.  cit.,  p.  121. 


240  THE    SOCIAL    IDEAL. 

are  the  lot  of  each  the  share  that  each  takes  in  the  evils 
of  others,  increases  the  sum-total  of  suffering  in  the 
world,  and  thus  comes  into  conflict  with  a  generally 
admitted  principle — that  progress  should  tend  to  a 
constant  increase  of  the  sum-total  of  happiness. 

Nietzsche  points  out  the  danger  that  humanity 
would  run  by  over-indulgence  towards  certain  forms 
of  suffering,  by  the  excessive  development  of  a  sensi- 
bility which  would  be  apt  to  become  morbid.  There 
is  an  unhealthy  sympathy  against  which  men  must 
become  fortified,  a  sympathy  displayed  by  neuro- 
paths for  beings  whom  a  little  severity  would  cause  to 
raise  themselves,  to  pluck  up  courage,  and  to  become 
useful  once  more  to  themselves  and  their  fellows. 
The  religion  of  suffering  may  serve  as  an  excuse  for 
many  of  these  weaknesses,  and  Nietzsche  has  stigma- 
tised "that  great  volume  of  pity  which  is  so  remark- 
able at  the  present  time"  as  a  manifest  index  of  an 
increasing  fear  of  that  suffering  without  which 
nothing  great  can  ever  be  done.  "  It  is  in  the  school 
of  suffering  and  of  great  suffering — do  not  you  know 
it  ? — and  it  is  under  this  hard  master  alone  that  man 
has  progressed.  You  would  like  if  possible  to  abolish 
suffering.  As  for  me,  I  should  like  to  see  a  harder 
and  worse  life  than  there  has  ever  yet  been."  In 
reality,  Nietzsche  wants  man  to  be  stronger  than  he 
has  ever  been,  to  be  triumphant  over  suffering,  and 
to  raise  himself  to  happiness  by  a  really  manly 
struggle,  and  this  part  of  his  doctrine  lacks  neither 
beauty  nor  depth  of  thought.1 

1  Cf.  Havelock  Ellis,  "Nietzsche,"  Affirmations.  —  ^^ 


THE   GOSPEL   OF   TOLSTOI.  24! 

1 1 6.  The  Gospel  of  Tolstoi. 

How  different  is  this  to  Tolstoi !  "  The  gospel  of 
Tolstoi,"  says  M.  Darlu,1  "differs  but  little  from  that 
of  the  Companions  of  the  New  Life,  assembled  at 
Boston  by  Thomas  Lake  Harris  a  quarter  of  a 
century  before. 

"  However,  it  seems  that  these  noble  ideas  of  pity, 
charity,  and  pardon  have  never  penetrated  so  deeply 
into  the  human  heart  since  the  days  of  Christ.  They 
have  impressed  on  our  sensibility  an  almost  painful 
vibration."  Tolstoi  has,  in  fact,  attempted  a  renais- 
sance of  Christianity,  while  Nietzsche  was  raising 
his  voice  with  energy  against  "a  morality  worthy 
of  slaves." 

What  seems  to  me  the  culminating  point  in 
Tolstoi's  theory  is  his  fourth  commandment  from 
the  Gospels.2  "  Evil  must  not  be  resisted,  but,  on 
the  contrary,  wTe  must  bear  with  every  insult,  and 
even  do  more  than  is  required  of  us.  We  must  not 
judge,  nor  must  we  have  part  or  lot  in  any  legal 
judgment,  since  every  man  is  himself  full  of  faults, 
and  has  no  right  to  teach  others.  By  taking  venge- 
ance we  teach  others  to  avenge  themselves." 

The  consequences  of  this  commandment  are  by 
non-resistance  to  evil  and  injury,  the  suppression 
of  the  whole  military  and  judicial  apparatus;  by 
the  refusal  to  take  part  in  a  lawsuit,  the  negation 
of  law  and  of  every  judicial  institution.  No  army, 
no  State,  no  Church,  no  means  of  coercion,  even  with 
respect  to  moral  persons ;  humanity  forming  a  whole, 
"  living  in  constant  contact  with  nature  and  at  work 
— that  is  to  say,  under  the  very  conditions  that  are 

1  op.  «>.,  p.  33-  2  p-  72. 

16 


242  THE    SOCIAL   IDEAL. 

necessary  to  peaceful  happiness,"  L  the  abandonment 
of  all  the  conquests  of  a  civilisation  which  is  detest- 
able from  its  moral  results — that  is  the  social  ideal 
conceived  by  Tolstoi,  corresponding  to  his  ideal  of 
individual  life;  happiness  in  the  " sympathetic  and 
free  "  labour  of  the  fields,  in  family  life,  and  in  the 
free  and  benevolent  relations  of  all  mankind. 

117.  Renunciation. 

Tolstoi  is  the  enemy  of  every  tendency  that  may 
awaken  jealousy  and  lead  to  strife  between  man  and 
man,  and  that  is,  no  doubt,  wrhy  he  condemns  the 
sexual  instinct,  while  glorifying  family  life.  "  Love," 
he  says  in  his  little  work,  The  Relations  between  the 
Sexes,  "  from  all  that  precedes  it  and  follows  it,  and 
in  spite  of  all  our  efforts  to  prove  the  contrary, 
both  in  prose  and  verse,  never  does  and  never  can 
give  the  means  of  attaining  an  object  that  is  worthy 
of  man;  it  is,  on  the  contrary,  an  obstacle  to  that 
end,  .  .  .  and  reason  shows  us  that  continence  is  the 
only  solution.  .  .  .  Now  let  us  suppose  that  chastity, 
the  Christian  ideal,  were  realised:  what  would 
happen  ?  We  should  find  ourselves  in  complete 
agreement  with  religion  and  science." 

No  doubt  Tolstoi,  later  on,  somewhat  moderated 

this  rather  bold  statement.    He  admitted  marriage  as 

a  consequence  of  the  "  first  common  fall,  considered 

^as  an  act  of  for  ever  indissoluble  marriage,"  but  on 

the  especial  condition  "  that  no  one  is  harmed  there- 

•  by."     Thus  he  presents  to  us  the  Christian   Pam- 

philus    confessing    to    the    pagan    Julius    his    deep 

affection  for  Madeleine,  but  at  the  same  time  men- 

1  Kovalevsky,  "  La  Morale  de  Tolstoi,"  in  Morale  sociale,  p.  176. 


RENUNCIATION.  243 

tioning  the  obstacle  which,  until  then,  had  prevented 
him  from  carrying  his  project  into  execution.  "  A 
young  man  of  my  acquaintance  is  also  in  love  with 
Madeleine.  He  is  a  Christian;  he  loves  both  of  us 
tenderly,  and  I  shall  never  consent  to  cause  him  pain 
by  robbing  him  of  every  hope.  Perhaps  I  shall 
marry  later  when  I  am  quite  convinced  that  no  pain 
will  be  caused  to  any  other  person."1  Such  a  re- 
nunciation of  love  in  the  presence  of  friendship 
would  have  nothing  surprising  about  it  if  it  were 
merely  a  question  of  an  exceptional  case,  in  which 
friendship  happens  to  be  stronger  than  love.  But 
Tolstoi  claims  to  lay  it  down  as  a  constant  rule,  by 
treating  as  brothers  all  those  who  place  far  above  the 
satisfaction  of  individual  appetite  a  good  understand- 
ing, reciprocal  confidence,  and  the  common  peace. 

And  just  as  he  has  sacrificed  sexual  love  to  the  love 
of  humanity,  Tolstoi  sacrifices  every  economical  and 
political  organisation  to  the  ideal  of  peace.  He 
dreams  of  a  patriarchal  life  from  which  all  commerce 
has  disappeared,  in  which  the  use  of  money  is 
banished  even  for  the  purpose  of  almsgiving. 
"  Every  use  of  money,  whatever  it  may  be,  is 
only  the  presentation  of  a  bill  of  exchange  drawn 
on  the  poor,  or  the  transmission  to  a  third  person 
of  a  bill  of  exchange  to  enable  him  to  pay  the  un- 
fortunate." Alms  will  never  cause  poverty  to  dis- 
appear: work  alone  can  do  that. 

"  I  ought  to  deprive  the  unfortunate  of  the  work 
that  they  do  for  me,  either  by  not  having  it  done 
for  me  at  all,  or  by  doing  it  myself."2  I  ought  to 
renounce  every  luxury,  everything  that  is  superfluous, 

1  Pamphile  et  Julius,  pp.  95-100. 

2  Tolstoi,  Que  Faire  ?  pp.  243-249. 


244  THE    SOCIAL    IDEAL. 

to  live  the  common  life  with  the  utmost  frugality, 
amid  the  riches  of  nature,  and,  as  M.  Gide  puts  it, 
in  a  "  homogeneous  and  amorphous  "  society. 

Tolstoi  is,  in  fact,  the  enemy  of  modern  science 
and  art.  "  The  sciences  ignore  the  questions  of  life. 
.  .  .  Science  and  art  have  failed  in  their  mission.  .  .  . 
Supreme  wisdom  has  other  bases  than  the  human 
intellect  and  science."1  His  philosophy  is  in  the 
highest  degree  a  philosophy  of  reaction  with  respect 
to  all  scientific  and  industrial  progress.  It  is  that 
of  a  peasant  who  has  made  a  praiseworthy  effort 
to  understand  and  to  practise  primitive  Christianity 
under  its  rudimentary  form  of  love  for  humanity. 
It  has  ignored  social  evolution  and  the  craving  for 
justice,  which  is  affirmed  with  increasing  energy  in 
the  conscience  of  the  humblest. 

118.  Consequences  of  Non-resistance  to  Evil. 

The  dogma  of  non-resistance  to  evil  is,  no  doubt, 
that  against  which  our  natural  tendencies  most 
vigorously  protest.  We  might  renounce  industrial 
progress  to  the  benefit  of  our  lives,  and  renounce  it 
the  more  easily,  inasmuch  as,  since  our  needs  increase 
with  the  resources  that  are  necessary  for  their  satis- 
faction, we  are  not  really  more  happy  from  the 
material  point  of  view  than  men  would  be  who  live 
the  frugal  life  of  the  fields.  But  we  cannot  give  up 
scientific  and  artistic  progress,  which  affords  an  ever- 
increasing  satisfaction  to  our  insatiable  desire  to  know 
and  to  feel. 

It  is  not  in  man's  nature  to  be  temperate  in  the 
acquisition  of  knowledge  as  he  is  temperate  in  food 

1  Tolstoi,  Pensles  choisies,  par  Ossip  Lourie,  pp.  108-112. 


NON-RESISTANCE    TO    EVIL.  245 

or  drink.  Intellectual  pleasures  differ  from  the 
pleasures  due  to  the  satisfaction  of  the  nutritive 
and  sexual  instincts,  inasmuch  as  one  is  never  tired 
of  them,  and  they  do  not  arise  so  much  from  the 
periodical  satisfaction  of  needs  that  are  being 
periodically  re-awakened,  as  from  a  sustained 
interest  and  a  permanent  tendency  which  is  never 
weakened. 

Intellectual  pleasures,  therefore,  constitute  a  benefit 
due  to  civilisation — a  benefit  we  expect  to  increase 
as  civilisation  progresses.  The  cause  of  civilisation 
must  be  defended  against  every  factor  of  reaction. 
It  is  not  so  much  our  individual  rights  as  the  rights 
of  humanity  that  must  be  safeguarded  against  those 
who,  being  in  the  midst  of  humanity,  might  disregard 
them. 

Non-resistance  to  evil  would  have  taught  our 
ancestors  submissive  resignation  to  the  worst  type 
of  brigandage;  it  would  have  placed  inferior  races  in 
complete  subjection  to  superior  races,  and  thus  would 
have  irreparably  compromised  the  future  of  humanity. 
No  doubt  we  may  try  to  substitute  a  state  of  peace 
for  a  state  of  war,  we  may  try  to  substitute  an  entente 
cordiale  and  reciprocal  good  feeling  for  the  violent 
claiming  of  rights  which  are  too  strictly  enforced  by 
some  to  the  detriment  of  others.  Man  tends  to  have 
less  recourse  to  violence,  and  to  substitute  arguments 
for  blows,  as  he  becomes  more  civilised,  more  fit  to 
use  his  reason. 

Violence  is  bad,  both  because  its  triumph  is  often 
opposed  to  reason  and  because  with  the  appeal  to 
violence  evil  is  multiplied.  But  blind  love  and  the 
renunciation  of  rights  are  not  without  dangers. 

In  many  cases  to  give  up  a  right  is  to  make  it  im- 


246  THE    SOCIAL    IDEAL. 

possible  to  accomplish  a  duty.  The  man  who  is  so 
fond  of  his  fellows  that  he  does  not  wish  to  cause 
them  pain,  will  be  found  in  many  circumstances  to 
be  compelled  to  cause  pain  to  one  person  in  order 
not  to  cause  it  to  another,  and  if  he  abstains  from 
action  he  may  cause  pain  to  both.  If  he  must 
choose  between  the  pain  he  will  give  to  his  wife, 
or  his  son,  or  his  brother,  and  the  pain  which  he 
may  give  to  one  of  his  fellow-creatures — perhaps 
almost  unknown  to  him — will  he  not  be  violating  his 
family  duties  if  he  prefers  the  happiness  of  the  un- 
known to  the  happiness  of  his  relative,  although 
charity  may  perhaps  command  him  to  serve  the 
interests  of  the  unknown  and  to  sacrifice  those 
nearest  and  dearest  to  him  ? 

To  abstain  from  criticism  is  to  abstain  from  con- 
flict; it  is  to  give  up  what  perhaps  is  the  finest 
element  in  human  activity — the  struggle  for  what 
one  considers  to  be  good,  the  defence  of  the  good 
against  the  evil.  Such  renunciation  must  be  due 
to  fundamental  apathy  or  to  great  discouragement. 
At  a  time  when  it  is  so  difficult  to  practise  tolerance, 
Tolstoi  comes  and  asks  us  to  carry  to  an  extreme 
a  virtue  which  we  barely  possess.  And  then,  when  we 
want  so  many  different  stimuli  to  move  us  to  action, 
Tolstoi  takes  them  away  from  us  and  asks  us  to 
regard  life  with  the  eyes  of  a  man  who  is  dying. 
In  fact,  the  man  who  is  dying  is  the  only  man 
who  has  not  to  take  thought  for  the  morrow,  who 
may  be  called  upon  to  return  good  for  evil,  for  he  need 
not  trouble  himself  to  know  whether  in  acting  thus 
he  is  favouring  the  evil  at  the  expense  of  the  good, 
and  injuring  the  cause  which  he  professes  to  serve. 
Or  rather,  he  is  no  longer  serving  any  cause;  his 


THE    NECESSITY    OF    CONFLICT.  247 

detachment  from  the  things  of  this  world  is  complete. 
He  thinks  of  nothing  more  but  how  to  lead  a  holy 
life,  such  as  one  would  lead  in  a  world  of  good  will. 

1 19.  The  Necessity  of  Conflict. 

Unfortunately,  perhaps,  the  man  who  wishes  to 
live,  and  whose  philosophy  is,  to  use  the  expression 
of  Spinoza,  a  meditation  on  life  rather  than  a  medita- 
tion on  death,  ought  to  prepare  himself  for  triumph 
and  to  assure  the  triumph  of  his  cause.  From  the 
moral  point  of  view,  the  important  thing  is  that  his 
cause  shall  be  a  good  one.  From  the  psycho-socio- 
logical point  of  view,  the  inevitable  thing  is  that 
he  is  serving  a  causej  and  that  he  is  exercising  on 
himself  and  others  an  inhibitive  power,  the  role  of 
which  is  at  least  as  considerable  as  that  of  positive 
activity. 

Nietzsche  has  therefore  taken  human  nature  and 
social  requirements  into  fuller  account  than  Tolstoi 
has  done,  if,  that  is  to  say,  Tolstoi  has  really  attempted 
to  take  them  into  account  at  all.  The  morality  of 
full  vital  expansion,  which  is  exactly  the  same  as 
Guyau's,  has  been  correctly  brought  into  relation  with 
that  of  the  Uebermensch,  a  morality  which  only  aspires 
to  give  life  its  full  significance,  and  which  is  the 
enemy  of  all  mysticism  and  pessimism.1 

"  Above  all,"  says  Nietzsche,  "  you  must  see  with 
your  own  eyes  where  there  is  always  the  most  in- 
justice, that  is  to  say,  where  life  has  its  meanest, 
most  restricted,  most  impoverished,  and  most  rudi- 
mentary development,  and  where  it  can  do  nothing 
but  take  itself  as  the  end  and  measure  of  things, 

1  "  The  cancer,"  as  Nietzsche  says,  "  of  the  old  ideals  and  heroes  of 
fiction,"  p.  13.  Preface  to  Menschliches,  Altzttmcnschliches. 


248  THE    SOCIAL    IDEAL. 

where  it  can  only  grumble,  and  in  a  secret,  petty,  and 
assiduous  manner,  question,  from  the  love  of  self- 
preservation,  what  is  noblest,  greatest,  and  richest — 
you  must  see  with  your  own  eyes  the  problem  of 
hierarchy,  and  the  way  in  which  power,  justice,  and 
width  of  perspective  increase  in  proportion  as  we 
become  elevated."1 

But  if  Guyau  tells  us  to  live  with  the  utmost  possible 
intensity,  Nietzsche  adds: — Live  in  your  own  way  the 
higher  life  you  have  chosen;  be  your  own  judge  and 
a  free  man;  be  a  creator  of  values  by  establishing  at 
first  in  your  own  mind  a  hierarchy  of  social  values,  as 
you  understand  them,  by  realising  them  afterwards  in 
the  face  of  every  obstacle,  by  throwing  into  subjec- 
tion the  low  herd  of  the  humble  who  cannot  determine 
for  themselves,  and  by  entering  into  conflict  with 
other  free  men,  your  equals,  who  are  likewise  creators 
of  values. 

1 20.  Despotism. 

"You  must  become  your  own  master,  the  master 
of  your  own  virtues.  Once  they  were  your  masters, 
but  they  have  no  right  to  be  anything  but  your 
tools  on  a  par  with  other  tools."2  The  Ueber- 
mensch,  then,  is  above  the  moral  law;  it  is  he  who 
makes  the  law;  upon  him,  a  new  Leviathan,  depends 
the  conception  that  the  whole  of  a  faithful  people 
forms  for  itself  of  good  and  evil,  of  virtue  and  vice. 

The  subjective  nature  of  moral  ideas  is  thus  clearly 
proclaimed,  and  the  most  surprising  part  about  it  is 
that  their  subjectivity  does  not  lead  us  to  moral 
anarchy.  M.  Fouillee,  asserting  that  doubt  is  possible 

1  Op,  cit.t  Part  I.     Preface,  p.  15.  2  Op.  «'/.,  p.  14. 


DESPOTISM.  249 

as  to  the  real  hierarchy  of  the  good,  concludes  there- 
from a  wide  tolerance,  a  perhaps  excessive  extension 
of  the  rights  of  the  individual  in  matters  of  belief  and 
action.  The  French  philosopher  even  extracts  quite 
a  system  of  morality  from  this  rather  negative  principle. 
When  in  doubt,  abstain.1  In  it  he  sees  the  origin  of 
individual  right,  of  liberty,  of  moral  respect,  and 
therefore  of  duty.  Max  Stirner2  (Caspar  Schmidt) 
exaggerates  these  consequences  of  subjectivism,  so  far 
that  he  will  have  nothing  to  do  with  liberty  that 
is  granted.  True  liberty,  he  says,  is  what  is  taken. 
And  thereby  he  closely  approaches  the  conception  of 
Nietzsche,  for  admitting  no  master,  no  law,  nothing 
superior  to  the  individual,  he  advises  his  hero  to 
"  desecrate "  everything  that  religion  and  morality 
have  consecrated;  to  have  none  of  the  prejudices  of 
his  age,  none  of  the.  weaknesses  of  his  so-called 
fellow-creatures  with  respect  to  civilisation,  the 
State,  the  Church,  the  city,  and  the  family.  The 
individual,  like  the  Uebermensch,  makes  his  own  law, 
and  treats  other  men  not  as  ends,  but  as  means  and 
instruments.3 

The  views  of  Nietzsche  are  more  complete  than 
those  of  Stirner,  so  far  as  politics  are  concerned. 
Those  of  the  latter  lead  to  anarchy;  those  of  the 
former  to  a  narrow  subordination  of  the  inferior  to 
the  superior  caste,  of  the  plebs  to  the  nobility,  through 
the  clergy,  army,  and  government.  The  classical 
conception,  notably  that  of  Plato,  thus  finds  in 

1  But  cf.   "  Les   concessions  a  1'absurde  .    .  .   peuvent   etre   parfois 
necessaires,"  etc.     Fouillee,  La  Morale  de  Guyau,  chap.  viii.  p.  180. 
— TR. 

2  Der  Einzige  und  sein  Eigenthum.     Leipzig,  1845- 

3  Zenker,  Anarchism,  chap.  iii. — TR. 


250  THE    SOCIAL    IDEAL. 

one  of  our  contemporaries  a  new  interpreter,  but 
with  this  difference,  that  while  Plato  believed  in 
an  objective  ideal,  and  a  world  of  Ideas  serving 
as  a  model  for  the  wise  man,  the  simple  instrument 
of  divinity,  Nietzsche  wants  his  wise  man  to  be  really 
an  original  legislator  and  creator.  It  is  no  longer, 
then,  the  Good  Shepherd,  the  representative  of  God 
on  earth,  whom  he  proposes  for  our  veneration;  he 
gives  the  whole  direction  of  life  to  the  aristocracy 
formed  by  independent  thinkers,  not  because  they 
are  wise,  learned,  and  prudent,  but  because  they 
are  strong  and  audacious,  and  because  their  will  is 
brutally  imposed  and  becomes  law. 

To  the  question  that  is  so  often  asked — whether 
might  is  right — Nietzsche  replies  with  Hobbes  and 
Spinoza  that  might  is  the  source  of  right.1 

"  Justice  originates  among  men  of  almost  equal 
power.  Where  there  is  no  power  clearly  recognised 
as  predominant,  and  where  conflict  would  only 
cause  reciprocal  and  futile  injury,  we  have  the  origin 
of  the  idea  of  discussion  and  agreement  on  the  claims 
of  both  sides.  The  character  of  the  exchange  is  the 
initial  character  of  justice.  .  .  .  Justice  is  a  com- 
pensation and  an  exchange  on  the  hypothesis  of 
almost  equal  power."2  Here,  then,  is  clearly  ex- 
pressed the  thesis  of  right  based  on  might  and  the 
reciprocal  neutralisation  of  contrary  forces.  "  Unus- 
quisque  tantum  juris  habet  quantum  potentia  valet." 

Nothing  is  more  disconcerting  to  the  reason, 
unless  we  admit  the  Spinozist  doctrine  which  gives 
power  to  a  being  in  proportion  to  his  rational  value. 

1  Vide  Austin,  Jurisprudence,   pp.   272  et  seq.,   Note  v.,   p.   284, 
Lecture  vi.,  and  cf.  Prince  Kropotkin,  Ahitual  Aid,  pp.   76-78. — TR. 

2  Memchliches,  Allzunienschliches. 


THE    MEEK. 


251 


But  the  might  that  was  in  Spinoza's  mind  differs 
totally  from  brute  force  as  conceived  by  Nietzsche. 
The  former  can  never  be  overcome  unless  it  is  reason- 
able that  it  really  should  be  suppressed;  the  latter 
can  always  be  suppressed  by  a  blinder,  more  irrational, 
and  still  more  brutal  force.  And  it  is  exactly  this 
oppression  of  intelligence  by  a  brute  force,  of 
reasonable  man  by  an  unreasonable  brute,  which 
is  hateful  to  us,  and  revolts  our  tendency  to  the 
subordination  of  the  unintelligent  to  the  intelligent. 
That  is  why  we  seek  for  the  law  another  foundation 
than  violence  or  the  equilibrium  of  forces  which  are 
ready  to  break  out  into  mutual  strife. 

121.  The  Meek. 

It  may  well  be  that  those  who  physically  were  the 
weakest  may  have  had  from  time  to  time  in  greater 
measure  than  the  strong  the  desire  of  seeing  morality 
and  law  opposed  to  violence.  Is  that  a  reason  for 
claiming  that  the  theoretical  rather  than  the  practi- 
cal realisation  of  their  desire  has  endowed  us  with  a 
"  morality  of  slaves,"  satisfactory  only  to  the  meek, 
to  those  with  feeble  will,  and  to  characters  of  inferior 
temper  ? 

Slaves  really  servile  have  never  had  the  slightest 
tendency  to  contrast  their  rights  as  men  with  the 
power  of  their  master.  True  slaves  are  those  whom 
Aristotle  so  admirably  depicts,1  happy  in  their 
servility,  with  no  depth  of  thought,  no  inclination 
for  the  life  of  free  men,  ever  requiring  to  be  guided, 
sustained,  and  ruled. 

Nietzsche   perhaps  was   not  wrong   in  his  desire 

1  Cf.  Politics,  vol.  i.  pp.  5,  13;  Economics,  I.  5.—  TR. 


252  THE    SOCIAL    IDEAL. 

that  masters  should  provide  for  the  happiness  of 
these  servile  souls  by  maintaining  them  in  obedience, 
and  imposing  upon  them  the  conceptions  of  free 
men.  There  is  surely  some  exaggeration  in  the 
conception,  born  with  Christianity  and  developed  by 
the  success  of  modern  democracy,  of  a  humanity 
in  which  all  individuals  have  equal  rights,  equal 
aptitudes  for  self-government  and  for  the  determina- 
tion of  the  destinies  of  all.  Ideas  of  equality, 
although  they  appear  generous,  are  sometimes 
Utopian;  and,  in  fact,  we  see  in  the  most  demo- 
cratic masses  a  real  subordination  of  those  whose 
minds  are  servile  and  whose  intellect  is  feeble,  to 
those  who  lead  them,  whether  by  right  or  by  sheer 
audacity. 

Demagogic  manners  and  morals  are  not  likely  to 
give  to  lofty  spirits  lasting  and  deep  tendencies  to 
an  effective  recognition  of  the  equal  rights  of  all 
men.  They  betray  too  much  hatred  in  the  many 
with  respect  to  the  limited  and  selected  few,  too 
much  levelling  down  in  spite  of  considerable  in- 
equalities, and  they  incessantly  make  us  dread  a 
regression  of  humanity  towards  the  forms  of  inferior 
civilisation,  for  what  dominates  and  most  easily  directs 
the  crowd  is  what  flatters  the  meanest  instincts  of 
the  multitude. 

And  it  is  in  this  way  that  aristocratic  tendencies  arise 
in  superior  minds  through  a  reaction  which,  perhaps, 
is  instinctive,  but  to  which  reflection  and  reason  give 
both  foundation  and  support.  The  Christian  ethics 
which  loom  so  large  in  the  eyes  of  the  meek  and  the 
poor  in  spirit  lack  moderation  in  their  glorification 
of  the  inferior  man.  It  has  rightly  recalled  to  each  of 
us  his  duty  of  humility,  and  has  changed  instinctive 


THE    ARISTOCRACY.  253 

and  spontaneous  sympathy  into  love,  into  a  senti- 
ment of  fraternity  which  surpasses  the  bounds  of  the 
city  or  the  State,  and  which  is  lavished  on  the  whole 
of  humanity.  The  exaltation  of  the  natural  love  of 
the  animal  for  his  congeners,  of  man  for  his  fellows, 
cannot  be  lightly  blamed;  but  there  is  another 
human  sentiment,  a  sentiment  too  elevated  to 
appear  in  the  brute  creation,  and  one  which  it 
seems  quite  lawful  to  develop — that  of  respect  for 
worth,  of  respect  increasing  with  worth  in  pro- 
portion as  the  stages  of  a  social  hierarchy  are 
ascended. 

122.  The  Aristocracy. 

If  man  had  not  been  led  by  his  nature  to  consider 
in  different  pleasures  and  in  different  forms  of  good 
the  objects  of  his  desires,  so  many  stages  in  a 
hierarchy  of  values,  he  would  have  never  deliberated, 
never  have  chosen,  never  have  willed ;  if  pleasures 
had  only  presented  to  him  quantitative  differences, 
he  would  only  have  tried  to  accumulate  them,  and 
to  juxtapose  them  one  with  another  in  the  course 
of  his  existence.  But,  in  reality,  the  idea  of  the 
best  has  been  from  all  time  the  directing  idea  of 
his  conduct,  even  when  his  appreciation  has  been 
at  fault. 

Social  evolution  shows  us  the  considerable  role 
played  by  this  idea  of  the  best  in  the  organisation 
of  common  life.  There  is  no  State  without  a 
hierarchy;  nowhere  is  the  crowd  homogeneous, 
everywhere  are  chiefs,  more  or  less  temporary, 
elected  or  hereditary,  springing  from  the  ranks  of 
the  people  or  from  a  caste  closed  to  the  multitude; 
even  in  our  own  days  and  in  countries  with  demo- 


254  THE    SOCIAL    IDEAL. 

cratic  customs  there  are  governing  classes  and  other 
classes  which  aspire  to  become  the  governing  class. 
These  are  commonplaces  of  history  and  observation. 
At  all  times  and  at  all  places  there  has  therefore  been 
a  social  hierarchy,  and  the  effective  sovereignty  of 
the  strongest  proceeds  in  most  cases  from  what 
has  been  considered,  from  a  given  point  of  view, 
the  best.  This  point  of  view  varies:  here  it  is  the 
best  soldiers,  there  the  best  orators,  elsewhere  the 
best  merchants,  the  notable  manufacturers  or  land- 
owners; but  everywhere  it  is  the  men  who  occupy, 
or  are  considered  to  occupy,  the  summit  of  a  scale 
of  social  values. 

Nietzsche  requires  the  masters  to  be  those  who 
have  established  this  scale  of  values,  and  who  have 
imposed  it  upon  the  popular  credulity;  but  history 
shows  that  the  scale  of  social  values  is  prior  to  the 
conception  held  of  them  by  the  men  who  are  at  the 
summit.  Napoleon  could  only  create  a  factitious 
nobility,  an  ephemeral  hierarchy,  although  he  reached 
the  summit  of  human  greatness.  The  will  of  a  man, 
however  powerful  he  may  be,  does  not  very  deeply 
modify  the  tendencies  of  the  multitude.  The  hypno- 
tised crowd  may  for  a  moment  follow  its  magnetiser, 
but  the  hypnosis  is  of  short  duration,  and  the  suc- 
cesses of  the  Ucbermensch  are  ephemeral. 

The  social  evolution  is  not  at  the  mercy  of  the 
caprice  of  genius;  very  rarely  indeed  are  the  tastes 
of  genius  those  of  the  crowd ;  the  hierarchy  of  values 
admitted  by  men  of  talent  and  science  is  not  that 
admitted  by  the  people. 

Is  it  necessary  to  remember  that  the  man  of  genius, 
the  saint,  the  prophet,  the  man  inspired,  the  tribune, 
affect  social  evolution  only  in  so  far  as  they  are 


THE    ARISTOCRACY. 


255 


products  of  that  evolution;  and  that,  so  to  speak, 
they  are  inserted  in  a  series  of  factors  of  the  col- 
lective future,  not  to  oppose  the  other  forces,  but 
to  accelerate  their  action,  and  precipitate  or  retard 
events  according  to  circumstances  ?  Is  it  necessary 
to  repeat  once  more  how  simple  is  hero-worship,  and 
how  powerless  is  even  the  strongest  human  will  to 
modify  the  natural  course  of  events  ?  If  Socrates, 
Jesus,  and  Mahomet  had  not  made  their  appear- 
ance at  the  "psychological"  moment,  would  they 
not  have  been  considered  by  posterity  as  visionaries, 
madmen,  or  at  least  as  eccentric  ?  Because  they 
had  a  place  marked  out  in  advance  for  them  at  the 
very  centre  of  events,  and  because  their  influence 
radiated  over  a  part  of  the  world,  each  was  a 
Uebermensch,  not  because  humanity  responded  to 
his  appeal,  but  because  he  in  some  measure 
responded  to  the  appeal  of  humanity. 

And  so,  when  Nietzsche  asks  us  to  recognise  as 
the  supreme  ideal  his  hero,  the  creator  of  a  scale  of 
values,  his  suggestion  is  impossible :  it  is  contrary  to 
the  teaching  of  sociology  and  history. 

Individuals  do  not  modify  their  environment  so 
much  as  their  environment  modifies  and  governs 
them.  The  freest  man,  the  man  who  is  most  deter- 
mined to  act  according  to  his  own  whim,  is  still,  in 
spite  of  it,  unconsciously  a  product  of  his  own  age 
and  of  his  own  country.  He  unconsciously  obeys 
collective  tendencies  and  common  prejudices  against 
which  he  often  cannot  react  because  he  does  not 
suspect  their  existence. 


256  THE    SOCIAL    IDEAL. 

123.  Importance  of  the  Theory  of  Rights. 

The  morality  of  Nietzsche  is  as  unacceptable  as 
that  of  Tolstoi ;  both  are  too  much  a  priori — the  one 
a  morality  of  abnegation,  the  other  a  morality  of 
might.  Both  abnegation  and  might  only  have  moral 
value  according  as  they  either  of  them  serve  a 
superior  and  well-defined  interest.  Renunciation  for 
the  sake  of  renunciation,  and  might  for  the  sake 
of  might,  are  not  the  mark  of  a  reasonable  being. 
We  must  know  how  to  sacrifice  ourselves,  or  how 
to  strive  for  a  social  ideal.  Nietzsche's  Uebermensch 
could  only  become  a  moral  being  by  agreeing  to  ful- 
fil duties  corresponding  to  his  power;  he  had  not  so 
much  to  create  a  hierarchy  of  values  as  to  subordinate 
the  order  of  social  values  to  the  order  of  social 
duties. 

It  is,  in  fact,  on  the  theory  of  the  rights  of  each 
individual  in  society  that  the  doctrines  of  Nietzsche 
and  Tolstoi  come  into  their  most  radical  conflict; 
here  both  lack  a  solid  foundation.  This  fact  is  a 
sign  of  the  importance  which  we  should  attach  to 
the  organisation  of  individual  and  collective  rights  in 
the  ideal  society. 


THE    FOUNDATION    OF    RIGHTS.  257 

IV. 

RIGHTS. 

124.  The  Foundation  of  Rights.1 

LIBERTY,  in  the  positive  sense  of  the  word,  is  Right. 
We  have  not  the  liberty  to  dispose  of  what  we  have 
the  right  to  possess;  we  have  only  the  liberty  to  do 
what  we  have  the  right  to  do;  all  other  liberty  is 
only  provisional,  precarious,  and  is  not  moral  because 
it  cannot  be  claimed.  The  increase  of  liberty  ob- 
tained in  the  course  of  evolution  is  therefore  an 
increase  of  individual  rights.  But  on  what  founda- 
tion do  these  rights  rest  ?  Are  they  simply  granted 
by  the  community  to  the  individual,  by  an  arbitrary 
decision  of  the  State,  or  of  the  power  acting  in  the 
name  of  the  community  ?  If  they  are  granted  with- 
out due  reason,  they  may  be  taken  away  again,  even 
if  consecrated  by  usage.  No  doubt  "customary 
right"  is  of  the  importance  that  the  " historical 
school"  has  thrown  into  such  bold  relief.  Rights 
which  result  from  morals,  from  local  or  district 
customs,  consecrated  by  the  social  consciousness 
which  has  maintained  them  for  numerous  genera- 
tions, notwithstanding  variations  and  fluctuations 
of  different  kinds,  run  the  least  chance  of  abolition; 
but  we  discovered  in  1789  that  they  are  not  protected 
during  revolutionary  movements. 

We  can  hardly  expect  rights  founded  on  fact  to 
be  maintained  except  by  force;  but  force,  however 
great  it  may  be,  cannot  be  assured  of  indefinite 

1  Austin,  op.  cit.,  Lecture  XVI. ,  pp.  393 


258  RIGHTS. 

supremacy;  and  besides,  as  Spinoza  pointed  out, 
there  is  no  individual  force  which  will  not  be  inferior 
to  social  power. 

125.  Natural  Right.1 

But  it  has  been  claimed  that  there  are  natural, 
inalienable,  imprescriptible  rights,  although  they  are 
often  misunderstood.  Such,  at  the  time  of  the  Re- 
volution, was  the  theory  which  was  inspired  in  parti- 
cular by  J.  J.  Rousseau.  Man  is  born  free — that  is 
to  say,  he  has  all  rights,  and  the  only  limit  set  to 
these  rights  is  the  requirement  of  respect  for  the 
liberty  of  others.  If  each  of  us  has  not  unlimited 
rights,  it  is  because  he  is  not  alone  in  an  unlimited 
world.  It  is  because  of  the  limitations  of  property 
and  the  multiplicity  of  free  beings  that  the  rights 
which  each  of  us  holds  from  nature  are  restricted  by 
life  in  society.  Slavery  and  despotism  have  been 
condemned  in  the  name  of  these  so-called  natural 
rights.  But,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  the  right  of  nature 
rests  upon  the  hypothesis  of  a  metaphysical  liberty. 
This  liberty  may  be  disputed,  for  all  metaphysical 
entities  have  no  well-established  objective  reality, 
and  men  in  general  will  always  be  tempted  to  ignore 
such  liberty,  because  for  the  most  part  they  cannot 
even  imagine  it. 

To  affirm  a  natural  right  is  to  presume  to  lay  down 
rights  a  priori,  and  nothing  is  more  dangerous  in 
politics,  nothing  is  more  contrary  to  the  scientific 
spirit. 

If  our  practical  conceptions  must  depend  on  the 
highest  conception  of  all — that  of  a  social  state  that 

1  Austin,  op,  cit.,  pp.  344  et  seq. — TR. 


RIGHTS    OF    SOCIAL    FUNCTION.  259 

we  are  obliged  to  realise  in  common,  ought  not  the 
idea  of  our  rights  to  flow  from  that  of  our  social 
duties  ? 

126.  Metaphysical  Right  and  Dignity. 

The  Kantians  admit  the  co-relation  of  rights  and 
duties,  and  the  priority  of  the  notion  of  duty  to  every 
other  moral  notion ;  but  they  generally  make  the  rights 
of  a  man  depend  on  the  duties  that  other  men  have 
towards  him,  and  notably  on  the  fundamental  duty 
of  respecting  " eminent  human  dignity"  at  all  times, 
in  all  places,  however  miserable  the  bearer  of  the 
moral  law  may  be  in  other  respects.1  Now  we  know 
that  this  "eminent  dignity"  of  which  Kant  speaks 
has  its  apparent  reason  in  the  power  of  duty,  and  its 
real  reason  in  the  "noble  source  and  the  noble 
origin"  of  moral  obligation,  Liberty,  the  ratio  essendi 
of  duty.  So  that  we  are  brought  by  a  detour  to 
rights  founded  on  metaphysical  liberty.  And  as  the 
liberty  of  each  is  not  precisely  fixed,  the  limitation 
of  individual  rights,  one  by  the  other,  becomes  rather 
a  question  of  fact  than  a  question  of  morality.  It 
follows  that  in  reality  there  is  in  such  a  doctrine  no 
principle  for  the  effective  determination  of  the  rights 
of  each.  Besides,  in  the  eyes  of  Kant  moral  obliga- 
tion is  indeterminate ;  therefore  the  right  which  is  its 
correlative  is  none  the  less  so.2 

127.  Rights  of  Social  Function. 

That  it  may  be  enforced  is  generally  considered  as 
the  characteristic  of  a  right.  The  idea  of  justice  is 

1  Cf.  Austin,  op.  cit.t  pp.  285,  712.— TR. 

2  Austin,  op.  cit.,  p.  713.— TR. 


260  RIGHTS. 

closely  connected  with  the  idea  of  legal  restraint  and 
penal  enactment. 

I  possess  a  right.  Then  you  must  all  respect  it. 
That  is  the  current  formula.  Looking  closer,  we 
see  that  the  right  is  a  consequence,  an  effect  and  not 
a  cause;  that  most  of  the  rights  that  we  claim  to 
have  respected  are  not  connected  with  the  person, 
but  with  the  social  function  that  the  person  is  sup- 
posed to  fulfil,  so  that  if  he  does  not  fulfil  the  function 
well  he  has  partially  forfeited  his  powers  and  his 
liberties. 

No  doubt  there  are  certain  rights  common  to  all 
men,  and  attached  to  the  human  person  in  general ; 
but  it  is  worth  noting  that  they  are  connected  with 
generous  impulses,  charity,  and  human  solidarity;  so 
that  if  honourable  men  could  not  agree  to  fulfil 
what  have  been  called  "wide  duties,"  most  of  the 
rights  of  man,  qua  man,  could  not  be  exercised,  and 
would  not  effectively  exist.1  It  is  out  of  "  humanity" 
that  we  concede  to  the  wretched  the  right  to  be 
pitied  and  consoled  for  their  misfortunes.  But  the 
right  to  the  free  expression  of  his  thought,  for 
instance,  really  only  belongs  to  the  citizen  who 
accepts  the  obligation  of  not  creating  disturbance 
in  the  State  by  his  wild  speeches.  Liberty  of  con- 
science is  not  a  right  of  man,  qua  man,  it  is  a  right 
of  the  ripened  man  who  has  reached  a  sufficient 
degree  of  intelligence  and  reason,  and  is  capable  of 
fulfilling  his  duties  as  a  good  citizen.  It  would 
therefore  be  important  at  the  outset  to  have  an 
exact  idea  of  the  totality  of  our  social  obligations. 
They  are  in  fact  of  three  types — those  imposed  upon 
us  by  laws  or  morals,  those  which  result  from  our 

1  "  Duty  the  basis  of  right,"  Austin,  op.  cit.,  p.  395. — TR. 


RIGHTS    OF    SOCIAL    FUNCTION.  261 

functions,  and  those  which  are  derived  from  our 
contracts. 

We  have  already  seen  that  those  which  are  im- 
posed upon  us  by  laws  or  customs  are  so  intimately 
connected  with  those  which  result  from  our  functions 
that  wre  can  scarcely  trace  a  line  of  demarcation 
between  the  two  domains.  Every  man  may 
consider  himself  as  a  function  of  the  social  state 
in  which  he  lives,  and  his  activity  as  a  function 
of  the  complete  social  activity.  There  is  there- 
fore no  reason  for  drawing  a  lasting  distinction 
between  the  rights  of  the  citizen  in  general  and 
the  rights  of  the  citizen  performing  a  public  func- 
tion; the  two  groups  can  be  united  in  one,  that 
of  the  citizen  fulfilling  under  every  circumstance 
his  social  function. 

As  for  the  rights  which  result  from  the  contracts 
between  individuals,  they  are  very  clearly  derived 
from  the  obligations  that  at  least  two  individuals 
accept  who  become  "functions"  one  of  the  other. 
In  every  contract  we  only  acquire  rights  over  others 
because  of  our  reciprocal  duties.  It  is  easily  seen 
that  the  rights  which  issue  from  contract  are 
very  varied,  and  that  they  do  not  depend  on  a 
moral  theory  except  in  so  far  as  they  depend  on  the 
theory  of  contract  in  general.  Now  the  latter,  as  we 
have  already  seen,  is  subordinate  in  fact  to  the  more 
general  right  that  the  State  claims  for  itself,  to  put  a 
check  to  the  liberty  of  the  contracting  parties,  by 
obliging  them  under  pain  of  judicial  nullity  to  observe 
forms  which  are  more  and  more  rigorously  deter- 
mined. The  problem  of  the  right  to  contract  thus 
raises  the  problem  of  the  rights  of  the  State  over  its 
citizens.  But  that  brings  us  to  the  question  of  the 


262  RIGHTS. 

foundation  of  rights  anterior  to  all  contract,  rights 
founded  on  the  exercise  of  a  social  function. 

Evolution  seems  to  sanction  the  increase  of  im- 
portance and  independence  of  the  individual  in  pro- 
portion as  the  division  of  social  labour  makes  him  a 
more  appreciable  factor  in  the  common  prosperity. 
History  shows  that  aptitude  to  possess  and  to  act 
freely  increases  with  the  aptitude  to  perform  obliga- 
tions corresponding  to  conceded  rights.  Under  the 
feudal  system  the  lord  had  many  rights,  because, 
theoretically  at  least,  he  had  many  duties.  Until 
1789  the  eldest  son  in  France  possessed  all  the 
family  property,  because  he  had  all  kinds  of  obliga- 
tions towards  his  brothers  and  sisters.  Everywhere 
an  exact  correspondence  tends  to  be  established 
between  rights  or  powers  conceded  and  obligations 
imposed.  Real  equity  appears  more  and  more  to 
consist  in  the  inequality  of  benefits  corresponding  to 
the  inequality  of  charges. 

128.  Justice  and  Devotion. 

And  so  we  are  led  more  and  more  to  feel  how 
complex  a  thing  is  justice.  "  Neither  the  mathema- 
tical idea  of  equality,"  says  M.  Tanon,  "  nor  that  of 
proportion,  of  equivalence,  and  of  reciprocity,  nor 
the  idea  of  harmony  and  beauty,  nor  that  of  the 
identity  and  agreement  of  thought  with  itself,  nor 
even  the  wider  idea  of  solidarity — each  and  all  of 
which  enter  in  some  measure  into  the  idea  of  justice 
— is  its  only  source;  they  do  not  suffice  to  exhaust 
its  rich  and  varied  content,  nor  to  respond  to  the 
warmth,  diversity,  and  force  of  sentiment  that  its 
evocation  awakens  in  the  minds  of  men." 


JUSTICE    AND    CHARITY.  263 

This  is  because  an  equitable  distribution  of  rights 
implies,  as  we  have  just  seen,  a  preliminary  equitable 
distribution  of  duties,  and  this  apportionment  on  the 
one  hand  can  only  take  place  in  virtue  of  a  general 
conception  of  the  social  system,  and  on  the  other 
hand  can  only  be  imposed  entirely  from  without  on 
individuals  whose  good-will  is  indisputably  a  factor 
of  the  highest  importance.1 

Obligations  which  are  incumbent  upon  each  of  us 
must  certainly  not  only  be  accepted,  but  must  be 
spontaneously  sought  by  the  really  moral  being,  to 
whom  we  give  considerable  liberty  and  initiative. 
According  to  the  precept,  "you  can,  and  therefore 
you  must,"  the  best  men  feel  themselves  morally 
obliged  to  perform  the  highest  functions  that  they 
are  capable  of  performing ;  and  that  is  why  we  find 
at  the  base  of  social  justice  the  generous  impulse  of 
the  man  wiio  loves  his  fellow-creatures,  and  who 
works  with  a  relative  disinterestedness  for  the 
common  happiness.  It  is  thus  that  we  find  socia- 
bility and  goodwill. 

129.  Justice  and  Charity.2 

Those  who  have  tried  to  draw  a  distinction  be- 
tween justice  and  charity  are  therefore  quite  wrong. 
The  sentiments  of  sociability,  and,  in  particular,  the 
love  of  others,  the  generous  desire  for  expansion  and 
well-doing,  are  the  most  efficacious  motives  of  deter- 
mination by  which  a  man  agrees  to  fulfil  obligations, 
or  effectively  decides  to  fulfil  them.  If  in  the 

1  On  the  Monadistic  and  Monistic  Views  of  Justice,  vide  Mackenzie, 
Social  Philosophy,  p.  134. — TR. 

2  Cf.  Mackenzie,  op.  cit.,  p.  265.— TR. 


264  RIGHTS. 

primitive  forms  of  social  existence  the  constraint 
exercised  by  the  collectivity  on  the  individual  has 
played  the  largest  part,  we  need  not  therefore  believe 
that  this  constraint  has  had  to  break  down  effective 
resistances  such  as  the  selfishness  developed  by  re- 
flection or  the  struggle  for  existence. 

Constraint  was  always  exercised  in  view  of  a  kind 
of  discipline  of  the  activity,  but  there  was  in  the 
primitive  social  organism,  as  in  the  animal  organism 
from  its  birth,  a  spontaneous  activity,  and  the  spon- 
taneity of  the  social  elements  was  all  in  favour  of 
altruistic  actions.  This  was  for  a  twofold  reason  :  in 
the  first  place,  because  selfishness  implies  reflection 
on  the  self,  on  its  own  value,  and  a  differentiation  of 
the  individuals  which  thus  have  different  ends  and 
tendencies;  and  secondly,  because  the  collective  senti- 
ments and  tendencies,  in  view  of  common  ends,  in 
consideration  of  the  common  good,  were  originally 
preponderant  in  the  individual  consciousness. 
Voluntary  immolation,  the  spontaneous  sacrifice 
of  personal  advantages,  and  often  of  life  itself,  to 
the  interests  of  the  tribe,  are  proofs  of  this.1 

The  primitive  subordination  of  individual  to  social 
ends,  and  therefore  the  fundamental  disinterestedness 
of  human  nature,  seems  to  us  to  be  established  by 
the  indisputable  predominance  of  sympathetic  mani- 
festations in  the  particular  course  of  action  of  isolated 
beings.  Primitive  man  has  not  yet  the  prejudice  of 
his  "eminent  personal  dignity";  he  sees,  less  for 
himself  than  for  the  whole  in  the  midst  of  which  he 
does  not  yet  clearly  distinguish  himself.  If  therefore 
he  has  no  merit  in  being  generous,  it  is  equally  true 
that  he  cannot  be  the  subject  of  rational  approbation 

1  Prince  Kropotkin,  op.  «?.,  passim. — TR. 


JUSTICE    AND   CHARITY.  265 

or  disapprobation  on  account  of  his  unreflecting 
generosity. 

This  generosity  is  not  synonymous  with  chanty: 
charity  implies  a  clearer  consciousness  of  the  moral 
value  of  individuals,  and  a  keener  desire  for  the 
perfection  of  others.  But  it  has  both  the  spon- 
taneity of  the  charitable  impulse  and  the  specific 
character  of  love. 

The  role  of  the  reason  and  of  custom  is  to  regulate 
further  the  sometimes  capricious  course  of  natural 
generosity,  and  for  that  purpose  to  provide  at  the 
outset  against  whatever  excess  may  appear  in  certain 
impulses.  Exactly  because  liberty  of  action  is  re- 
strained, charity  cannot  manifest  itself  in  all 
directions.  The  individual  learns  to  exercise  over 
himself  a  kind  of  check,  and  justice  springs  from  a 
twofold  inhibitive  power,  one  external  and  the  other 
internal,  when  increasing  individualism  involves  the 
selfish  consideration  of  rights.  The  being,  until  then 
devoted  to  the  interests  of  the  community,  reflects 
on  his  own  interests,  contrasts  the  latter  with  the 
former,  and  claims  from  others  the  respect  due  to 
his  rights,  while  for  the  first  time  he  recognises  in 
an  explicit  manner  the  rights  of  his  fellows  to  receive 
from  him  the  services  that  he  formerly  rendered 
them  spontaneously. 

The  law  consecrates  this  evolution  of  the  general 
conscience,  and  recognises  that  respect  for  certain 
of  the  most  general  rights  may  be  claimed  if  need 
be  by  force ;  while  respect  for  other  and  more  vari- 
able and  disputable  rights  is  not  guaranteed  by  it. 
Hence  the  distinction  which  has  played  its  part  in 
classical  morality,  between  "strict  duties"  or  justice, 
and  "wide  duties"  or  charity;  as  if  the  accomplish- 


266  RIGHTS. 

ment  of  certain  obligations  could  be,  from  the  moral 
point  of  view,  more  or  less  obligatory;  as  if  one 
could  discuss  with  one's  conscience  and  reason  the 
degree  of  the  moral  necessity  of  certain  acts.  It 
should  be  understood  that  the  distinction  is  drawn 
between  duties  that  may  be  required  under  all 
circumstances,  and  duties  which  are  imposed  only 
under  certain  conditions ;  but  the  latter  would  none 
the  less  be  duties  as  imperative  as  the  others,  at 
certain  times,  and  in  certain  determinate  places. 

It  is  objected  that  the  duties  of  charity  are 
dictated  by  the  heart ;  but  we  have  just  shown  that 
generosity  is  the  common  source  of  all  duties,  and 
we  cannot  admit  that  because  an  impulse  of  the 
heart  has  become  a  prescription  of  the  reason  and 
the  law,  it  differs  fundamentally  from  the  impulse  of 
the  heart  which  may  become  a  prescription  of  the 
reason,  without  being  for  a  very  long  time  to  come 
a  prescription  of  the  law.  And  further,  the  generous 
impulses,  which  alone  are  ratified  by  reflection,  have 
a  moral  value;  in  a  well-organised  society  every- 
thing that  reason  and  generosity  combined  require 
the  law  must  tend  to  demand,  in  order  that  the 
domain  of  legal  obligations  and  the  domains  of  social 
and  moral  obligations  may  exactly  correspond,  since 
there  is  no  reason  for  their  being  fundamentally 
distinct. 

To  sum  up :  the  origin  of  rights  is  the  same  as 
that  of  duties.  All  rights  and  all  duties  are  of  the 
same  moral  importance,  and  a  being  possesses  no 
rights  but  those  which  he  holds  directly  or  indirectly 
from  the  obligations  which  are  incumbent  on  him, 
either  from  a  social  obligation  determined  by  custom 
and  natural  evolution,  or  by  his  spontaneity  as  a  moral 


THE    RIGHT    OF    PROPERTY.  267 

being,  considering  labour  at  the  common  task  as  a 
duty  in  proportion  to  his  strength,  his  capacity,  and 
his  natural  or  acquired  aptitudes.  And  so,  not  being 
able  to  claim  .liberties  and  possessions  except  in  so 
far  as  we  claim  obligations  compelling  those  liberties 
and  possessions,  we  have  an  exact  idea  of  our  rights 
from  the  exact  idea  of  the  duties  which  we  consent 
to  fulfil. 


130.  The  Right  of  Property.1 

No  right  is  more  interesting  than  the  right  of 
property.  By  what  has  been  just  said  this  right  is 
the  free  disposition  of  suitable  means  for  the  fulfilling 
of  a  duty.  To  what  duty  corresponds  what  has  been 
called  "  the  right  of  the  first  occupant  "  ?  This  so- 
called  right  is  that  of  the  chiefs  who  have  divided 
among  themselves  a  territory;  that  of  the  farmers, 
shepherds,  hunters,  fishers,  who  have  taken  posses- 
sion of  a  more  or  less  vast  tract  of  soil ;  that  of  the 
nations  who  occupy  by  means  of  their  explorers 
uncultivated  and  uninhabited  territories.  It  is  not 
enough  to  say,  as  the  Kantians2  and  individualists  in 
general  seem  too  prone  to  affirm,  that  in  taking 
possession  of  property,  the  possession  of  which  is 
undisputed,  we  harm  no  one,  we  injure  no  other 
person's  right,  and  we  only  use  our  personal  right 
to  extend  the  dependencies  of  one's  ego  as  far  as  is 
possible  without  injuring  the  liberty  of  others.  The 
absence  of  competition  is  a  negative  condition.  It 
does  not  found  a  right.  It  is  not  the  same  as  the 

1  Spencer,  Principles  of  Sociology,  chap,  xv.;  Austin,  op.  fit.,  p.  847; 
Maine,  Ancient  Law,  pp.  244-304. — TR. 

2  Cf.  Austin,  op.  cit.,  pp.  940  et  seq. — TR. 


268  RIGHTS. 

duty  that  we  assume  when  we  take  possession  of  a 
piece  of  land,  or  when  we  take  possession  of  a  piece  of 
flint  which  can  be  made  into  an  axe — the  duty  to  use  it 
with  the  view  of  giving  value  to  a  piece  of  natural 
property,  to  draw  from  it  a  profit  for  oneself  and  for 
others,  for  one's  own  cause  and  for  the  cause  of 
civilisation,  to  make  of  it,  in  short,  a  means  of  work. 

The  obligation  that  we  agree  to  fulfil,  in  the 
absence  of  any  other  man  who  claims  to  fulfil  it 
better  or  as  well,  incontestably  gives  a  right  which 
can  be  affirmed  by  resistance  against  any  one  who 
may  wish  to  expropriate  the  first  occupant.  But  this 
resistance  has  necessarily  its  limits.  For  if  there 
appears  an  individual  or  a  community  capable  of 
making  the  soil  or  the  tool  yield  more  for  the  good 
of  all  than  the  first  occupier  can  obtain  from  it,  his 
right  is,  so  to  speak,  superseded  by  theirs.  In  organ- 
ised society  we  see  that  under  such  circumstances 
an  expropriation  •  takes  place,  requiring  legal  forms 
at  first,  and  a  legal  indemnity  afterwards.  This 
duty  is  consecrated  by  the  "  Declaration  of  the 
Rights  of  Man,"  when  it  asserts  that  "  property 
being  an  inviolable  and  sacred  right,  no  one  can  be 
deprived  of  it,  save  when  public  necessity,  legally 
established,  evidently  demands  it,  and  then  only  with 
the  consent  of  a  just  and  previously  determined 
indemnity."  It  is  not  always  a  rigorously  inviolable 
property  which  may  be  taken  from  its  possessor 
without  indemnity;  and  that  is  exactly  why,  for  the 
expropriation  to  be  just,  the  right  of  possession  must 
be  essentially  based  on  a  duty  of  setting  a  value  on 
the  duty  of  labour,  in  the  wide  sense  of  the  word. 

And  it  is  this  same  duty  which  enables  us  to  con- 
ceive of  possession  as  lawful — that  is  to  say,  the  free 


THE    SHARE    OF    THE    COMMUNITY.  269 

disposition  of  the  tools  of  labour.  We  want  every 
man  to  fulfil  his  function,  and  we  ought  therefore  to 
leave  him  the  power  of  using  at  his  own  convenience 
those  tools  or  raw  materials  which  are  indispensable 
to  him  for  that  purpose. 


131.  The  Share  of  the  Community. 

Can  we  say,  for  instance,  that  the  possession  of  a 
machine  can  ever  be  absolute  property  ?  That 
machine  represents  a  large  number  of  inventions 
which  constitute  a  social  property,  a  collective 
capital.  This  machine  could  not  have  been  con- 
structed without  the  co-operation  of  a  large  number 
of  citizens  who  have  run  risks,  have  shown  devotion 
and  skill,  and  these  are  things  which  are  not  paid 
for;  the  possessor  of  this  instrument  of  labour  is 
therefore  indebted  much  more  than  is  generally  sup- 
posed to  society,  to  the  community,  for  that  property 
which  he  claims  to  be  his  own,  but  which  is  rather 
a  part  of  the  public  property  placed  in  his  hands. 

And  so  it  is  with  landed  property.  The  field  that 
you  say  is  yours,  and  that  you  surround  with  so 
much  care  by  high  walls  or  strong  hedges,  owes  the 
greatest  part  of  its  value  to  the  roads  which  are  near 
it,  and  \vhich  the  community  has  built  and  main- 
tained, to  the  railways  which  enable  you  to  bring  to 
it  the  agricultural  machines  which  are  necessary  for 
proper  cultivation ;  it  owes  its  fertility  to  processes 
that  you  did  not  invent,  to  tools  that  you  did  not 
create,  and  to  the  multitude  of  means  which  you  owe 
to  society,  much  more  than  to  your  ow^n  labour. 
Hence  the  fruit  that  you  reap  is  not  absolutely  your 
own.  Labour  in  the  sense  of  personal  activity 


270  RIGHTS. 

cannot  therefore,  as  many  moralists  and  politicians 
maintain,  found  an  absolute  right  of  property. 

"  Labour,"  says  M.  Renouvier,1  "  gives  as  it  were 
to  the  result  obtained  an  individual  consecration,  a 
seal  of  personality  which  adds  to  the  proprietary 
character  of  an  object  used  for  the  first  time 
and  necessary  to  life."  It  is  an  exaggeration  of  the 
scope  of  the  rights  of  the  individual  to  the  detriment 
of  the  rights  of  the  community,  whose  services  and 
preponderating  share  in  private  activity  we  are  far 
too  apt  easily  to  forget.  We  do  not  work  for  our- 
selves alone ;  we  work  for  the  whole  of  society ;  we 
do  our  share  of  collective  work,  and  we  may  there- 
fore be  the  less  disinterested  in  that  work  in  propor- 
tion as  division  of  labour  is  more  advanced. 

132.  Property  and  Reform. 

But  we  work  qua  individuals  capable  of  reform  and 
of  intelligent  and  free  activity;  we  are  not  machines, 
and  the  dignity  of  the  reasonable  being  can  only  be 
safeguarded  if  we  leave  to  the  worker  liberty,  free 
disposition,  and  property  in  his  means  of  action. 
Let  the  worker  become  less  and  less  a  machine,  an 
automaton,  acting  on  others  and  with  others;  this 
will  make  desirable  the  principle  already  laid  down 
of  an  increase  of  individual  liberty.  Property  in 
the  fruits  of  labour  is  less  imposed  than  that  in  the 
instruments  of  labour. 

No  doubt  it  is  quite  fair  that  each  should  enjoy 
advantages  proportionate  to  his  work;  but  it  is 
equally  fair  that  each  should  receive  means  of  action 
proportional  to  his  value,  to  his  capacities  or  apti- 

1  Sc.  de  la  Morale,  vol.  ii.  p.  12. 


HEREDITARY    TRANSMISSION    OF    PROPERTY.      271 

tudes,  to  the  importance  of  the  duties  that  it  is 
reasonable  for  him  to  attempt  to  fulfil.  Property 
in  certain  means  of  action,  such  as  land,  machinery, 
or  tools,  is  further  based  on  a  foundation,  though 
slightly  different,  yet  at  least  as  well  assured  as  that 
of  the  individual  possession  of  the  fruits  of  labour, 
or  of  the  money  which  is  the  customary  equivalent. 

The  right  of  individual  property  is  therefore  estab- 
lished for  all  beings  without  distinction.  The  in- 
equality of  the  rights  of  property  is  equally  well 
established.  On  the  one  hand,  let  us  give  to  each 
according  to  his  proved  aptitudes,  capacity,  and 
activity;  on  the  other  hand,  according  to  his  merits. 
It  would  be  absurd  to  grant  the  free  disposition  of 
considerable  property  to  an  idiot  or  to  a  being 
incapable  of  useful  social  work. 

It  is  therefore  the  duty  of  society  to  work  without 
relaxation  at  the  just  redivision  of  material  property. 
It  must  endeavour  to  procure  property  for  all,  and  to 
those  who  can  render  the  greatest  services  to  society 
it  should  guarantee  the  possession  of  sufficient  re- 
sources. The  right  to  labour,  which  was  so  ill-con- 
ceived in  1848,  when  it  led  to  the  creation  of  national 
workshops,  is  also  the  right  to  property.1 

133.  The  Hereditary  Transmission  of  Property. 

Is  not  the  right  of  hereditary  possession  an  obstacle 
to  the  fair  redivision  of  the  means  of  labour  which 
constitute  property  par  excellence  ?  On  what  founda- 
tion can  be  based  the  hereditary  transmission  of 
property,  if  not  on  the  duty  of  the  preceding  genera- 
tion to  secure  for  its  successor,  family  by  family,  the 

3  Mackenzie,  op.  cit.,  pp.  268  et  seq. 


272  RIGHTS. 

resources  that  are  necessary  for  the  accomplishment 
of  a  social  work  which  is  ever  becoming  more 
complex  and  more  elevated  ? 

If  inheritance  of  property  has  as  its  aim  to  ensure 
to  descendants  happiness  in  idleness,  it  must  be  con- 
demned as  contrary  to  the  first  duty  of  the  citizen, 
which  is  action,  the  production  of  property  destined 
to  secure  to  society  a  continual  increase  of  the  happi- 
ness of  all.  Morality,  therefore,  cannot  justify  the 
hereditary  transmission  of  wealth  which,  when  mis- 
placed, serves  no  longer  as  a  means  of  labour.  It 
cannot  approve  of  the  accumulation  in  a  few  hands 
of  enormous  capital,  which  permits  of  idleness  and 
vice,  without  involving  corresponding  obligations. 

On  this  point  as  on  all  others  it  is  therefore  neces- 
sary to  regularise  the  course  of  the  social  future,  in 
order  to  prevent  enormous  rights  of  property  from 
existing  without  the  acceptance  by  the  possessor,  or 
the  imposition  upon  him,  of  corresponding  social 
duties.  It  is  not  a  question  of  entirely  suppressing 
the  right  of  the  hereditary  transmission  of  property, 
although  this  right  does  not  repose,  as  has  been  said, 
on  an  absolute  right  of  the  testators  to  do  with  their 
fortune  what  pleases  them,  or  on  the  duty  of  respect- 
ing the  will  of  a  deceased  proprietor.  There  is  no 
absolute  property;  the  individual  only  possesses  by  a 
delegation,  so  to  speak,  made  to  him  by  society  of 
a  certain  quantity  of  means  of  action.  But  this 
delegation  naturally  persists  when  the  reasons  which 
at  first  determined  it  still  persist,  and  when  in  the 
children  are  to  be  found  aptitudes  at  least  equivalent 
to  those  of  their  parents. 

Hereditary  transmission  had  its  raison  d'etre  under 
the  ancient  regime,  when  the  inheritance  of  pro- 


HEREDITARY   TRANSMISSION    OF    PROPERTY.      273 

fessions,  posts,  and  offices  involved  the  inheritance 
of  the  means.  It  has  its  raison  d'etre  again  as  the 
importance  of  professional  inheritance  decreases ; 
for  if  the  parents  of  the  old  regime  were  preoccupied 
in  preserving  or  buying  for  their  children  posts  and 
dignities,  the  parents  of  to-day  are  occupied  in 
assuring  to  their  sons  or  daughters  not  titles 
but  aptitudes,  not  places  but  functions,  in  which 
they  will  have  to  display  intelligence,  sensibility, 
activity,  and  talent ;  and  therefore  the  more  right 
the  fathers  of  other  days  had  of  leaving  to  their 
children  the  means  of  triumphing  over  difficulties 
which  are  always  reappearing,  the  more  that  duty 
rests  upon  the  fathers  of  to-day.1  The  solidarity 
of  successive  generations  is  thus  formed  in  the  family 
in  a  moral  manner,  on  condition  that  it  has  as  its 
end  virtue  and  not  inaction. 

The  solidarity  of  the  members  of  the  same  com- 
munity may  be  affirmed  in  the  same  way,  and  from 
it  results  the  right  of  bequest,  which  is  a  correlative 
of  the  duty  of  social  education.  But  it  is  easily 
understood  that  as  this  duty  may  under  many  cir- 
cumstances be  misinterpreted,  the  right  of  bequest 
ought  to  be  limited  and  controlled  in  order  that  the 
intentions  of  testators  may  never  be  in  conflict,  and 
may  never  issue  in  results  contrary  to  those  just 
arrangements  which  are  made  by  society  to  secure 
an  equitable  redivision  of  the  means  of  action  among 
all  individuals. 

If  a  right  considered  as  absolutely  inviolable,  such 
as  the  right  of  property,  may  thus  be  limited  by  the 
exercise  of  collective  action,  we  see  that  all  other 

i  "  For  the  Effect  of  the  Abolition  of  Inheritance  upon  Culture,"  etc., 
vide  Mackenzie,  op.  cit.,  p.  272. — TR. 

18 


274  THE    STATE. 

rights  have  only  a  relative  value,  and  may  undergo 
incessant  fluctuations;  and  that  their  extension 
depends,  at  least  as  far  as  the  rights  of  the  individual 
are  concerned,  on  the  increase  of  the  personal  value, 
of  the  value  that  the  Kantians  take  as  absolute,  but 
which  is  being  ever  increased  by  the  unceasing 
development  of  human  intelligence  and  industry. 


V. 

THE  STATE.1 

134.  The  Role  of  the  State. 

WE  have  just  seen  how  close  is  the  dependence, 
both  in  fact  and  in  right,  in  which  society  holds  the 
individual ;  in  fact,  although  the  social  contract 
may  have  ceased  to  be  the  oppression  of  early  ages, 
and  in  right,  because  society  has  duties  to  fulfil. 
No  subject,  then,  can  be  of  more  importance  to  us  at 
this  stage  in  our  investigations,  than  that  of  the 
determination  of  the  powers  of  the  State. 

In  reality  there  is  only  one  right  that  the  State 
can  exercise,  that  of  legislation.  It  is  that  right 
which  enables  it  to  have  ministers  who  are  formed 
into  a  Government,  and  magistrates  who  are  the 
interpreters  of  its  sovereign  will.  The  ideal  law, 
being  the  prescription  of  reason  itself,  has  ipso  facto 
every  right  over  man.  If  a  man  is  only  moral  in 
obeying  according  to  his  nature  as  a  reasonable 
being,  he  is  only  moral  in  obeying  the  law.  But 
whence  comes  the  right  of  the  State  to  determine 

1  ''For  Definitions  of  the  State,"  cf.  Holland,  Jurispmdence,  p.  40; 
Austin,  op.  cif.,  p.  242. — TR. 


THEORIES    OF    SOVEREIGNTY.  275 

the  law,  and  to  impose  upon  the  race  its  will  and  its 
decisions? 

135.  Theories  of  Sovereignty.1 

There  are  many  theories  of  the  sovereignty  of  the 
State.  Aristotle,  in  the  second  chapter 2  of  the  third 
book  of  his  Politics,  attempts  to  justify  the  rule  which 
requires  that  in  a  democracy  the  majority  shall 
govern : — "  That  the  supreme  power  should  be  lodged 
with  the  many  may  be  satisfactorily  explained,  and 
although  it  may  not  be  free  from  difficulties,  it  seems, 
however,  to  contain  an  element  of  truth."  Among 
the  Romans,  the  will  of  the  prince  had  the  force  of 
law  only  because  the  people  delegated  to  him  full 
powrer.3  The  principle  of  the  sovereignty  of  the  people 
is  therefore  maintained,  although  an  individual  may 
be  considered  as  capable  of  as  much  wisdom  as  the 
many.  But  the  Roman  Church  was  not  long 
before  it  contested  the  sovereignty  of  the  State. 
Gregory  VII.  and  St.  Thomas  Aquinas  taught  that 
the  State  is  an  accursed  thing,  or  at  least  that  its 
power  is  of  purely  human  invention.  The  Church  of 
God  alone  is  the  depositary  of  power;  it  alone  is 
invested  with  the  right  of  dictating  laws  to  man.4 

Bodin,5  in  his  De  Republica,  admits  as  beyond  dispute 

1  Vide  Austin,  op.  cit.,  pp.  220  et  seq.\  and  for  criticism  of  Austinian 
doctrine,  vide  E.  Robertson,  Art.   uLaw,"  jfi*fjv.  Brit.y  xiv.  p.  356. 
— TR. 

2  III.,  chap,  xi.— TR. 

3  "Cum  populus  ei  et  in  eum  omne  imperium  suum  et  potestatem 
concessit."     Inst.,  Bk.  I.  ii.  6.— TR. 

4  The  Eternal  Opposition  of  Revelation  and  Reason. 

5  He  defines  the  Sovereign  part  of  the  State  as  ll  Summa  in  cives 
ac    subditos    legibttsque    soluta    potestas    .   .  .    quant     Graeci    &Kpai> 
t%ov<riav,  Kvplav  apxyv,  Kijpiov  TroXi'reu/ua,  Itali  Segnioriam  appellant.'* 
De  Rep.  i.  8.— TR. 


276  THE    STATE. 

"the  absolute  and  perpetual  power  of  the  republic"; 
in  his  mind  its  sovereignty  is  indivisible  and  inde- 
feasible. "  Ea  jura  nee  cedi,  nee  distrahi,  nee  ulla 
ratione  alienari  posse."  Of  all  the  rights  of  the 
sovereign  (whether  one  or  more)  the  principal  is 
"  the  power  of  giving  laws  to  subjects  without  their 
consent."  As  early  as  1609,  Althusius,  in  his  Politico, 
methodice  digesta,  promulgates  the  theory  of  the 
sovereignty  of  the  State  as  based  on  contract.  The 
State  is  the  last  of  a  series  of  contracts,  a  series  which 
first  comprises  the  family,  the  corporation,  the  com- 
mune, and  the  province.  Sovereignty  is  defined  as 
the  "highest  and  most  general  power  of  disposing 
of  everything  connected  with  the  safety  and  the 
well-being  of  the  soul  and  body  of  every  member  of 
the  Republic."1  The  people  is  the  great  political 
creator,  the  real  "king-maker";  the  force  which 
concedes  the  power  remains  superior  to  the  power 
it  concedes.  The  people  is  immortal.  It  is  there- 
fore the  unique  subject  of  a  permanent  power. 
Contract  is  rather  implicit  than  explicit.  If  the 
interpretation  placed  upon  it  by  the  legislature  is 
not  in  conformity  with  the  will  of  the  people,  then 
the  people  have  the  right  to  depose  the  legislature. 

Grotius  denies  that  the  sovereignty  of  the  people 
is  inalienable;  a  nation  may  with  its  own  consent  be 
reduced  to  complete  slavery.2  Hobbes3  declared  that 
the  people  never  did  possess  the  supreme  power 
before  it  gave  itself  a  master;  the  act  by  which 
are  established  both  sovereignty  and  the  legislative 

1  Politico.,  chap.  ix.  125. 

2  Grotius,  De  jure  belli  ac  pads  (i.  3,  8;  ii.  5,  31;  22,   u),  vide 
Austin,  op.  tit.,  p.  234. — TR. 

3  Cf.  Austin,  op.  tit.,  p.  235  ;  Holland,  op.  cit.,  p.  45.-  TK. 


THEORIES    OF    SOVEREIGNTY.  277 

power  is  the  contract  by  which  the  renunciation 
by  individuals  of  all  their  rights  was  effected. 
Never  was  this  idea  more  clearly  expressed — that  the 
State  is  something  official,  a  "  being  of  reason  "  on 
which  all  rights  are  conferred  with  a  view  to  the 
general  happiness  and  maintenance  of  peace  among 
men.  Having  admitted  that  peace  is  the  greatest 
good,  the  State  having  as  its  function  this  supreme 
good  must  dispose  of  all  power.  Locke  does  not 
admit  that  the  State  has  an  absolute  sovereignty; 
each  individual  retains  some  liberty.  To  Rousseau 
the  general  will  alone  is  the  right  will.  The 
sovereignty  of  the  people  is  inalienable  and  in- 
defeasible, but  it  cannot  be  exercised  by  delegation ; 
the  general  will  is  one  and  indivisible.  "  There  is 
not,  and  there  cannot  be,  any  kind  of  fundamental 
law  obligatory  on  the  mass  of  the  people,  not  even 
the  social  contract;"1  but  this  contract  gives  to  the 
body  politic  absolute  power  over  all  its  members.2 

The  historical  school  rejected  the  idea  of  the  social 
contract,  and  made  of  the  State  a  natural  product  of 
collective  evolution.  To  Burke,  Hugo,  and  Savigny,3 
the  power  of  the  State  was  the  result  of  tradition 
and  custom.  Kant  did  not  admit  the  historic  reality 
of  the  social  contract,  but  in  his  opinion  all  real  law 
must  be  such  as  it  would  have  been  if  the  general 
will  had  served  as  its  basis.  The  idea  of  the  absolute 
sovereignty  of  the  popular  will  reappears  clearly  in 
the  theory  that  the  legislative  power  has  all  rights 
and  no  duties  with  respect  to  the  citizens;4  that 

1   Contrat  social,  i.  7.  2    Ibid.,  ii.  4. 

3  Cf.  Robertson,  op.  cif.,  p.  363.  — TR. 

4  Kant,  (Euvres  (edit.  Rosenkranz),  vi.   165.     Cf.   Thtorie  du  Droit 
(1797). 


278  THE    STATE. 

there  are  no  means  of  coercion  which  can  be  em- 
ployed against  the  sovereign,  and  therefore  that  no 
constitutional  restriction  or  limitation  can  be  made 
to  the  power  of  the  monarch.  As  Mr.  Merriam 
has  remarked  in  his  recent  History  of  the  Theory  of 
Sovereignty  since  Rousseau,"1  Kant's  doctrine  of  the 
power  of  the  State  is  as  absolute  as  that  of  Hobbes 
and  Rousseau. 

Fichte  admits  a  series  of  contracts  by  which 
property  is  progressively  constituted,  and  by  which 
protection,  union,  and  subjection  to  the  government 
are  effected.2  This  subjection  has  for  its  end  the 
establishment  of  an  authority  capable  of  protecting 
the  rights  of  the  citizen,  an  authority  which  must  be 
watched  and  which  may  be  annihilated  by  a  con- 
stitutional assembly.  "  In  fact  and  in  right,  the 
people  is  the  sovereign  power,  the  source  of  all  other 
power,  and  responsible  to  God  alone."  To  Schel- 
ling,  the  State  is  the  consummation  of  a  cosmic 
process  [which  has  for  its  aim  the  reconciliation  of 
necessity  and  liberty,  the  realisation  of  an  absolute 
will,  "the  immediate  and  visible  type  of  absolute 
life."  Schelling  was  one  of  the  promoters  of  the 
movement  in  favour  of  the  divine  right  of  kings. 
In  the  opinion  of  many  theorists  on  that  right,  the 
theory  of  the  sovereignty  of  the  people  \vas,  as  De 
Bonald  holds,  a  theory  intimately  connected  with 
atheism  and  materialism.  The  supreme  power  can 
only  come  from  God ;  the  sovereign  is  the  representa- 
tive of  Providence,  and  his  rights  are  as  unlimited  as 
those  of  God. 

Hegel  conceived  the   State  as  a  real   personality 

1  Columbia  University  Press,  1900. 

2  Grnndlage  des  Naturrechts,  \  796-97. 


SUMMARY    OF   THE    THEORIES.  279 

having  rights  and  duties.1  This  being  has  "  its 
foundation  and  cause  in  itself."  It  is  a  person  moral 
to  a  higher  degree  than  an  individual.  It  is  the 
sovereign  person,  which  may  find  its  expression  in 
an  individual,  and  which  may  be  made  objective  in 
a  king. 

The  revolution  of  1848  based  sovereignty  on 
reason,  and  recognised  an  absolute  sovereignty  in 
the  "universality  of  the  citizens."  In  1832  Sis- 
mondi,  agreeing  with  Lerminier,  had  said:  " National 
reason  is  something  much  higher  than  public  opinion." 
According  to  Pierre  Leroux,  "  sovereignty  is  the 
power  which  descends  from  God  into  the  human 
mind  and  is  manifested  in  the  people;  that  is  to 
say,  by  the  indivisible  unity  of  all  the  citizens,  the 
real  image  of  Him  from  whom  it  flows."2  Proudhon 
held  that  sovereign  justice  results  from  organisa- 
tion, and  is  a  natural  product  of  the  constitution  of 
the  community,  just  as  health  is  a  resultant  of 
the  constitution  of  the  animal.  "  It  need  only  be 
explained  and  understood  to  be  affirmed  by  all  and 
to  act;"  to  it  "  belongs  the  direction  of  power."3 

136.  Summary  of  the  Theories. 

Such  are  the  principal  opinions  advanced  by  the 
theorists  with  the  object  of  legalising  the  rule  of 
the  State,  whatever  its  representative  may  be — king, 
parliamentary  assembly,  popular  assembly,  elective 
body,  hereditary  nobility,  etc.  Three  great  theories 
disengage  themselves  from  the  whole.  The  first 

1  Grundlinien  des  Philos.  des  Rechts  (1821),  sects.  35-36. 
-  Projet  oTune  Constitution  democratique  (1848),  art.  19. 
3  De  la  Justice  dans  la  Revolution^  \.  118. 


280  THE    STATE. 

bases  the  rights  of  the  State  on  the  rights  of  the 
Godhead ;  the  second,  on  the  popular  will,  whether 
that  will  be  or  be  not  considered  as  illuminated 
by  reason ;  and  the  third,  on  that  natural  evolution 
which  issues  in  the  constitution  of  an  organ  or  of 
a  kind  of  judicial  personality. 

The  first  of  these  great  doctrines  brings  us  to  the 
legalisation  of  every  arbitrary  decision.  When  we 
entrust  to  a  man,  or  to  a  privileged  body,  the  duty  of 
interpreting  the  divine  commandments,  or  of  making 
known  the  divine  will  and  of  substituting  himself  for 
Providence,  we  ought  to  trust  blindly  to  this  represen- 
tative of  the  Godhead.  We  implicitly  confess  our 
ignorance,  our  inability  to  know,  our  irremediable 
mental  and  moral  weakness ;  we  find  ourselves  in  a 
flock  for  which  we  cannot  even  choose  the  shepherd. 
But  by  what  sign  are  we  to  recognise  the  elect  of 
God  ?  Here  every  criterion  is  at  fault.  That  is  to 
say  the  whole  theory  is  wrong  from  its  foundation. 
The  second  doctrine  is  really  worth  consideration  only 
because — with  Rousseau,  Kant,  Pierre  Leroux,  and 
Proudhon — the  general  will  is  represented  as  the  most 
capable  of  right  decision.  But  the  obstacle  is  precisely 
the  unsurmountable  difficulty,  so  well  pointed  out  by 
Rousseau,  of  realising  the  unanimity  of  the  citizens. 
How  can  we  disengage  the  "  national  •  reason  "  of 
which  Sismondi  speaks  from  "  the  public  opinion, 
which,  although  in  general  far-seeing  enough,  is 
often  rather  precipitate,  impulsive,  and  capricious  "  ? 
Where  shall  we  find  "  this  reason  illuminated  by  all 
the  intelligence,  and  animated  by  all  the  virtues 
which  exist  in  the  nation  ? " 


SOVEREIGNTY   AND    THE    SOCIAL    CONTRACT.      281 

137.  Relative  Sovereignty  and  the  Social  Contract. 

If  we  cannot  find  it,  we  must  give  up  the  theory 
of  an  absolute  sovereignty,  which  could  be  only 
justified  by  an  absolutely  right  will.  We  must 
admit  a  limited  and  incomplete  sovereignty  corre- 
sponding to  the  imperfect  intelligence  illuminating 
the  State.  Hence  two  conceptions  are  admissible : 
either  the  sovereignty  is  transferred  from  the  nation 
to  an  elected  king,  responsible  himself  or  through  his 
ministers,  who  is  the  first  organ  of  political  life ;  or, 
it  is  transferred  to  a  picked  body,  whose  mission  is  to 
decide  in  the  name  of  all — to  a  Parliament  formed  of 
representatives  of  the  whole  country.  In  any  case 
the  organ  created  to  take  the  place  of  the  direct 
administration  of  the  people  by  itself,  the  vicarious 
representative  of  the  sovereign  power,  has  never 
had,  as  Althusius,  Locke,  and  Rousseau  saw  clearly 
enough,  as  many  rights  as  the  sovereign  people  itself, 
which  grants  to  it  all  needful  authority,  but  not 
absolute  po\ver.  Thus  there  are  grounds  for  placing 
limits  on  the  rights  of  the  State,  contrary  to  the 
admission  of  Hobbes  and  Grotius  in  their  desire  to 
legalise  the  absolute  power  of  the  king,  whom  they 
frankly  substituted  for  the  true  sovereign. 

But  most  of  those  who  have  admitted  national 
sovereignty  have  believed  in  a  social  contract,  im- 
plicit or  explicit,  and  ipso  facto  they  have  given  as 
a  moral  foundation  to  the  authority  of  the  State  a 
kind  of  delegation  made  to  it  by  individuals  of  a 
portion  of  their  power  and  right.  Neither  Rousseau 
nor  Kant  believed  that  this  contract  has  ever  been 
realised ;  they  none  the  less  considered  the  State 
as  able  to  claim  no  authority  other  than  that 


282  THE    STATE. 

of  the  individuals  composing  it.  The  opinion  of 
M.  Fouillee  does  not  sensibly  differ  from  that  of 
Kant,  in  the  sense  that  while  making  of  the  social 
contract  an  ideal  of  spontaneous  agreement  with  par- 
ticular wills,  M.  Fouillee  remains  an  individualist, 
and  refuses  to  seek  the  raison  d'etre  of  the  whole  any- 
where but  in  an  artificial  grouping  of  its  elements. 

No  doubt  the  force  of  the  State  must  more  and 
more  be  based  on  the  agreement,  the  "  synergy  "  of 
individual  wills ;  but  the  existence  of  the  State  is 
assured  in  fact,  and  is  legalised  on  other  principles. 
At  the  beginning  of  human  civilisation,  social  con- 
straint was  sufficient  to  create  a  central  power  in 
every  aggregate.  As  social  constraint  diminished, 
the  permanent  action  of  the  State  continued  to 
make  itself  felt  by  individuals,  as  we  have  pointed 
out  above,  in  spite  of  the  progressive  substitution  of 
a  contractual  right  for  a  purely  repressive  penal 
right.  The  more  important  the  contract,  the  more 
the  role  of  the  State  has  increased  from  the  judicial 
point  of  view,  so  true  it  is  that  legislative  and  con- 
tractual activity  are  entirely  distinct. 

138.  Duties  of  the  State. 

The  existence  of  a  legislative,  executive,  or  judicial 
power  does  not  then  depend  on  the  will  of  men ;  the 
State  is  a  natural  product,  a  natural  being,  as  op- 
posed to  Hobbes'  Leviathan,  a  monster  imposed  by 
reason. 

We  thus  come  to  the  third  of  the  great  doctrines 
concerning  the  State  which  we  mentioned  above. 
No  doubt  it  wras  not  sufficient  to  say  with  the 
"  historical  school "  that  traditions  and  customs 


DUTIES    OF   THE    STATE.  2$  > 

confer  political  power,  and  determine  the  nature 
as  well  as  the  extent  of  the  rights  of  the  sovereign ; 
but  it  must  be  recognised  that  the  evolution  of  the 
State  has  as  much  importance  as  the  evolution  of 
every  other  natural  being.  We  must  therefore  not 
endeavour  to  conceive  a  priori  a  r6le  and  rights  of 
which  history  will  teach  the  future.  Further,  Hegel, 
by  insisting  on  the  moral  value  of  the  State,  on  its 
rights  and  its  duties  as  well  as  on  its  supremacy,  its 
independence,  the  priority  of  its  power  relatively  to 
individual  liberties,  has  broken  completely  with  the 
theorists  of  the  social  contract,  although  his  idealism 
has  been  approached  by  all  those  who  claim  that  the 
State  has  the  sovereignty  because  it  is  the  best  repre- 
sentative of  the  impersonal  reason,  and  the  best  judge 
of  the  objective  value  of  maxims,  precepts,  customs, 
traditions,  collective  tendencies,  and  morals. 

We  can  therefore  reconcile  naturalism  and  idealism 
by  considering  the  State,  whatever  be  the  form  of 
government,  as  having  in  the  highest  degree  the  right 
of  regulating  morals,  of  penetrating  into  private  life, 
not  because  individuals  consent  to  it,  but  because  it 
is  by  nature  and  by  right  the  highest  organ  of  the 
reason,  and  the  fittest  instrument  to  establish  the 
rule  of  the  reason  over  man.  But  \ve  must  beware 
of  absolutist  conceptions. 

The  State  has  rights,  just  as  individuals  have, 
within  the  limits  within  which  it  can  fulfil  its 
duties.  Now,  can  it  assume  the  responsibility  of 
every  individual  act,  and  even  of  a  large  number  of 
collective  acts  ?  If  it  could,  it  would  be  because  in- 
dividuals or  communities  have  no  right  of  initiative, 
no  obligation  to  reform  in  order  to  contribute  to 
social  progress.  But  invention  is  the  doing  of  in- 


284  THE    STATE. 

dividuals,  not  of  the  State,  which  has  no  imagination  ; 
so  that  individual  minds  must  collate  the  common 
data  in  their  own  fashion,  and  must  meet  at  the  point 
of  intersection  of  those  great  lines  of  imitation,  which, 
to  quote  the  saying  of  M.  Tarde,  are  like  the  rivers 
which  irrigate  the  sociological  domain. 

The  rights  of  the  State  can  only  therefore  be  such 
as  to  infringe  on  individual  rights,  by  a  reformation 
prudent  or  rash,  unfortunate  or  fruitful,  and  destined 
to  modify  more  or  less  considerably  an  aspect  of 
social  life.  But  they  ought  to  be  wide  enough  to 
prevent  the  propagation  of  those  "  pernicious  novel- 
ties" against  which  all  governments  have  made  it 
their  business  to  protect  themselves,  as  soon  as  they 
have  detected  in  them  the  revolutionary  spirit. 

Here,  then,  is  the  problem  of  the  moral  right  of 
citizens  to  revolt  against  a  government  which  has 
obstinately  persisted  in  reaction,  or  of  resistance  to 
social  progress.  Such  a  government  evidently  over- 
steps its  rights,  and  either  it  ceases  to  be  the  real 
minister  of  the  State,  or  the  State  injures  the  rights 
of  individuals,  and  goes  to  its  ruin  through  ignorance 
of  its  true  role ;  in  the  latter  case  the  constitution  of 
the  State  on  new  foundations  is  necessary,  and  we 
must  go  back  to  the  real  sources  of  sovereignty  to 
found  a  new  political  right.  Such  is  the  moral  office 
of  revolutions,  which,  when  lawful,  are  attempts  made 
by  the  greatest  number  to  harmonise  the  effective 
r6le  of  the  State  and  the  rational  conception  of  that 
role,  at  a  given  moment  of  the  social  evolution. 

The  present  moment  seems  a  suitable  time  for 
giving  to  the  central  power  a  very  complex  social 
mission — that  of  social  organisation  in  every  stage.1 

1  Cf.  Spencer,  Principles  of  Sociology,  chap.  xxii.  2  — TR. 


DUTIES    OF   THE    STATE.  285 

"  The  more  societies  are  developed,"  says  M.  Durk- 
heim1  (and  this  quotation  only  sums  up  what  we 
have  said  above  of  the  evolution  of  the  central 
power),  "  the  more  the  State  develops;  the  more 
and  more  numerous  become  its  functions,  and  the 
further  it  penetrates  into  all  the  other  social  func- 
tions which  it  ipso  facto  concentrates  and  unifies. 
The  progress  of  centralisation  is  parallel  to  the  pro- 
gress of  civilisation.  ...  It  may  be  said  that  there 
is  no  more  firmly  established  historic  law."  It  is 
the  State  which,  "  as  it  has  assumed  the  powrer,  has 
freed  the  individuals  belonging  to  particular  and  local 
groups  which  tend  to  absorb  it,  such  as  the  family, 
city,  corporation,  etc.  Individualism  and  '  Statism  ' 
have  marched  in  history  side  by  side." 

If  the  State  cannot  be  a  despot,  having  all  rights 
over  the  individual,  and  if  it  ought  to  be  freer  in  pro- 
portion as  it  has  carried  out  more  obligations,  it  has 
acquired  more  value  of  its  own,  and  it  is  imperative, 
as  M.  Coste  has  so  clearly  laid  down,2  that  the 
central  power  should  be  more  and  more  "the 
liberator "  of  the  moral  person.  "  It  is  a  question 
of  preventing  usurpation  and  monopoly;  of  main- 
taining harmony  and  holding  the  balance  betwreen 
particular  interests,  and  of  resisting  eccentric  and 
divergent  enterprises."  In  the  same  order  of  ideas, 
M.  L.  Stein  assigns  to  the  State  as  a  transient  obliga- 
tion the  duty  of  decreasing  all  abnormal  power  which 
may  check  the  permanent  interests  of  civilisation. 

Now  the  conflict  of  the  living  forces  whose  synergy 
is  indispensable  to  common  life  may  compromise  the 
future  of  humanity.  It  means  disorder  in  the  present 
and  radical  discontinuity  in  the  future.  The  State 

1  Rev.  Phil.,  1899,  t.  xlviii.  p.  438.  '  Op.  «'/.,  p.  190. 


286  THE    STATE. 

must  therefore  extend  at  once  the  maximum  of 
rational  organisation,  and  must  henceforth  proceed 
with  the  regular  increase  of  future  social  organisa- 
tion. Politics  is  an  art  of  foresight  as  much  as 
wisdom.  To  be  conscious  of  a  collective  ideal,  to 
expound  it  with  the  utmost  clearness  to  every  mind, 
and  thereby  to  instruct  and  guide  in  the  realisation 
of  a  work  of  progress,  is  one  of  the  first  duties  of  a 
governing  body. 

The  State  ought  to  be  the  focus  of  light  which 
illumines  and  revives,  which  guides  and  protects. 
It  has  the  right  of  struggling  against  everything 
which  is  radically  opposed  to  union,  harmony,  and 
progress.  That  is  why  it  must  regulate  all  modes 
of  activity  and  existence  into  which  an  immoral 
force  might  bring  disturbance,  and  which  it  might 
guide  in  a  wrong  direction. 

The  weak-minded  man  makes  a  false  inference. 
Let  the  law  protect  him  from  himself,  for  in  so  far  as 
he  is  badly  advised  he  may  injure  himself  and  injure 
others.  The  isolated  individual  may  be  exploited 
by  the  usurer,  capitalist,  or  the  unscrupulous,  who 
profit  by  their  power  to  impose  upon  him  conditions 
that  are  contrary  to  justice  and  humanity — let  the 
law  declare  null  and  void  contracts  thus  imposed  by 
force.  What  is  dangerous  for  the  individual  is  the 
sect  which,  forming  a  kind  of  closed  community, 
imposes  progressively  on  its  members  obedience, 
renunciation,  and  sometimes  crime.  Let  the  associa- 
tion be  free  but  not  tyrannical;  the  law  should,  in 
this  case  more  than  in  others,  protect  the  individual 
in  the  midst  of  a  blind  multitude  subject  to  the 
domination  of  a  few  intriguers,  and  as  such  capable 
of  any  kind  of  excess. 


THE    STATE    AND   ASSOCIATIONS.  287 

139.  The  State  and  Associations. 

Association  in  general,  far  from  being  proscribed, 
ought  to  be  encouraged;  for  when  it  is  open  and 
remote  from  the  sectarian  spirit,  when  it  imposes  on 
the  individual  no  sacrifice  either  of  his  dignity,  his 
just  rights,  or  his  moral  independence,  it  constitutes 
the  most  efficacious  protection  against  the  despotism 
of  the  central  power.  The  State  should  aim  at 
organising  resistance  against  all  oppression,  even 
against  that  which  a  government  might  attempt  in 
its  name. 

The  French  Revolution,  unfortunately,  miscon- 
ceived this  duty  of  the  State.  It  proscribed 
associations  after  having  destroyed  the  corporations, 
which  had  made  themselves  odious  precisely  because 
they  were  in  some  measure  "  privileged  aggrega- 
tions," in  which  despotism  reigned,  and  thus  it  made 
" unions"  for  a  long  time  impossible.  But  we  are 
coming  back  to  a  healthier  notion  of  the  rights  and 
duties  of  the  State  as  far  as  association  is  concerned. 
"  What  frees  the  individual,"  says  M.  Durkheim1 
again,  "  is  not  the  absence  of  every  regulating 
principle,  but  their  multiplication,  provided  that  the 
multiple  centres  are  co-ordinated  and  subordinated 
the  one  to  the  other."  The  State  has  therefore  the 
right  to  protect  young  associations,  since  thus  it 
fulfils  its  duty  of  protection  with  respect  to  indi- 
viduals. It  will  even  find  before  long,  as  M.  Paul 
Boncour2  puts  it,  a  valuable  auxiliary  in  unions  of 
every  kind,  which  only  submit  their  members  to 
special  discipline  in  order  that  they  may  submit 
themselves  to  common  discipline,  so  that  each  nation 
1  Loc.  cit. ,  p.  239.  2  Le  Federalism*  economique. 


288  THE    STATE. 

will  form  a  kind  of  federation  of  associations  which 
will  already  have  completed  the  initial  task  of  social 
unification. 

The  State  will  then  be  able  to  intervene  in  the 
affairs  of  the  community  and  of  the  elementary 
social  group,  not  in  order  to  stifle  its  life  and 
spontaneity,  but  to  regularise  its  activity,  and  to 
place  it  in  harmony  with  the  activity  of  the  other 
organs  of  social  life.  It  is  thus  that,  to  use  M. 
Tarde's  expression,  it  will  complete  its  part  of 
"  initiator  "  by  its  function  as  "  regulator." 

140.  The  State  as  Educator. 

But  in  so  far  as  it  is  an  initiative  power,  will 
it  not  be  the  duty  of  the  State  to  take  proper 
measures  for  the  development  of  the  aesthetic,  re- 
ligious, scientific,  and  moral  sentiments,  which  are 
as  it  were  the  vital  principles  of  the  "  social  body," 
the  essential  appetitions  of  the  common  conscience  ? 
Does  it  not  follow  that  there  ought  to  be,  for 
instance,  a  State  religion,  an  official  instruction  in 
theological,  scientific,  and  moral  truth  ?  The  question 
is  that  of  the  duties  and  rights  of  the  State  in  matters 
of  education  and  collective  belief. 

We  have  already  agreed  that  the  social  evolution 
of  the  collective  sentiments  tends  to  increase  inces- 
santly the  love  of  science,  to  diminish  the  ardour 
of  religious  belief,  and  to  extinguish  fanaticism  and 
intolerance.  Is  it  necessary  to  oppose  social  evolu- 
tion on  this  point,  and  to  endeavour  to  restore  unity 
of  religious  belief?  What  moral  interest  could  such 
a  reaction  afford  us  ? 

Religious  unity  cannot  give  us  moral  unity,  for, 


THE    STATE    AS    EDUCATOR.  289 

as  we  have  already  said,  the  same  religious  practices 
may  be  in  accordance  with  quite  different  forms  of 
conduct,  some  moral  and  some  immoral ;  and 
further,  theological  conceptions  are  so  vague  and  so 
difficult  to  accurately  define,  that  their  subjectivity 
will  always  be  an  obstacle  to  identity  of  belief;  in 
short,  the  history  of  religion  is  a  history  of  schism, 
heresy,  and  heterodoxy  of  every  description.  In 
proportion  as  the  modern  mind  penetrates  further 
into  Christian  thought,  we  find  that  thinkers  more 
readily  admit  of  free  discussion.  M.  Sabatier,  the 
Dean  of  the  Faculty  of  Protestant  Theology  at 
Paris,  declared  some  years  ago  that  orthodoxy  in  the 
Reformed  Religion  is  sheer  nonsense. 

The  State  cannot,  therefore,  consider  it  as  one  of 
its  rights  to  establish  religious  unity.  Can  it  con- 
sider as  one  of  its  duties  the  equal  encouragement 
of  every  form  of  religious  manifestation  ?  To  those 
who  think  that  religion  is  necessary  to  social  life,  we 
may  raise  the  objection  that  public  manifestations  of 
any  theological  creed  whatever  are  of  a  nature  to 
wound  the  independent  conscience,  and  a  fortiori  that 
of  those  who  have  a  different  religion  from  that  of 
which  we  may  encourage  the  development.  For 
believers  in  general  are  convinced  that  they  alone 
possess  the  truth,  and  they  consider  it  their  duty  to 
combat  error.  The  characteristic  of  a  collective 
belief  being  to  manifest  itself,  one  may  anticipate 
conflict;  and  we  may  fear  that  the  intervention  of 
the  State  in  the  discussion  of  the  causes  of  trouble 
may  not  lead  to  the  end  proposed,  namely,  to  the 
harmony  of  all  social  forces  and  the  co-operation  of 
every  form  of  energy. 

And  besides,  the  absence  of  well-established   re- 


THE    STATE. 

ligious  truth,  an  absence  which  would  make  intoler- 
able the  re-establishment  of  a  State  religion,  removes 
worship  and  belief  from  the  collective  conscience  and 
makes  of  it  an  essentially  private  matter.  The  inno- 
vations and  modifications  that  a  citizen  thinks 
should  take  place  in  traditional  ceremonies  concern 
himself  alone,  and  can  only  interest  the  State  in  so 
far  as  the  happiness  or  the  unhappiness  of  the 
citizens  as  a  whole  may  depend  upon  particular  acts 
of  piety  or  impiety.  There  is,  therefore,  no  reason 
to  oppose  the  evolution  which  makes  of  religious 
sentiments  something  more  and  more  foreign  to  the 
collective  conscience,  and  which  reserves  for  them  a 
safer  asylum  in  the  individual  conscience. 

It  is  almost  the  same  with  the  aesthetic  sentiments. 
There  can  be  no  official  art  without  outrage  to  the 
individual  right  of  free  appreciation  of  works  of  art 
and  of  independent  taste.  But  the  case  of  scientific 
sentiment  is  entirely  different.  Science  consists  of 
objective  truths  and  of  assertions  that  may  be  veri- 
fied again  and  again.  It  is  to  the  public  interest 
that  scientific  truth  be  established  and  extended,  that 
the  worship  of  the  true  be  universal,  and  that  citizens 
be  initiated  into  that  worship  from  their  earliest 
years.  It  is,  therefore,  the  duty  of  the  State  to  see 
that  scientific  instruction  is  given  to  all,  in  order  to 
multiply  the  means  of  investigation  and  discovery, 
and  to  extend  in  all  directions  the  idea  of  fresh  con- 
quests of  human  reason  and  of  methodical  experi- 
ment. How  far,  then,  may  be  carried  the  right  of 
the  State  in  matters  of  instruction  ?  Can  it  compel 
its  citizens  to  receive  such  instruction  as  their  minds 
can  understand,  can  it  reserve  to  itself  the  right  of 
directing  study  and  forming  their  minds  ?  This  right 


THE    STATE    AS    JUDGE. 

seems  incontestable.  Is  not  the  duty  of  knowing 
rational  and  scientific  data  closely  connected  with 
that  of  obeying  the  reason,  and  has  not  the  State 
which  ought  to  protect  the  individual  the  right  to 
arm  him  for  his  own  protection,  especially  when  the 
arms  that  are  furnished  serve  the  material  and  moral 
interests  of  the  community  ?  Just  as  the  State 
should  take  measures  of  general  protection  against 
physical  harm,  poverty,  and  disease,  ought  it  not  to 
take  measures  of  general  protection  against  intel- 
lectual mischief,  ignorance,  and  error  ?  And  if  it  is 
therefore  its  duty  to  watch  over  the  instruction  of  all, 
it  has  the  right  to  organise,  to  direct,  and  to  apportion 
instruction  according  to  the  interests  which  the  social 
system  has  to  realise.  No  doubt  it  has  not  the 
power  to  prevent  any  one  from  learning,  or  from 
learning  more,  but  it  has  the  right  to  compel  each 
individual  to  learn  as  much  as  the  individual  degree 
of  intelligence  and  attention  permits.  With  this 
right  of  making  instruction  obligatory  in  general  is 
connected,  for  instance,  the  right  of  imposing  military 
instruction  for  the  defence  or  the  safeguard  of  all,  in 
whatever  form  and  at  whatever  time  is  found  suitable. 


141.  The  State  as  Judge. 

And  finally,  the  State  in  the  same  way  is  supposed 
to  be  provided  with  the  wisdom  that  is  requisite  to 
make  the  laws  and  to  determine  the  duties  of  the 
citizen;  just  as  it  is  considered  the  born  protector 
and  the  born  instructor  of  all  individuals,  so  it  is  the 
natural  distributor  of  justice.  Hence  its  duty  to 


2Q2  THE    ECONOMICAL    ORGANISATION. 

establish  a  magistracy,  and  its  right  of  making 
arrests,  to  which  when  effected  in  its  name  every 
citizen  is  liable.  This  magistracy  is  twofold:  part 
is  administrative,  and  part  is  judicial.  For  the  rights 
of  the  State  to  be  indisputable,  in  so  far  as  it  com- 
pels respect  to  its  magistrates,  administrators,  or 
judges,  it  has  one  last  duty  to  fulfil,  that  of  choosing 
as  interpreters  of  the  law  men  who  are  thoroughly 
qualified  both  by  their  mental  lucidity  and  by  their 
sense  of  equity. 


VI. 

THE  ECONOMICAL  ORGANISATION. 

142.  Competition. 

IT  is  in  the  economic  order  that  the  intervention  of 
the  State  seems  likely  to  produce  important  results 
in  the  future.  This  intervention  was  for  a  long  time 
considered  as  likely  to  produce  more  disturbance 
than  benefit;  it  was  thought  that  the  domain  of 
economic  facts  is  the  domain  of  competition  between 
individuals.  It  would  therefore  have  been  necessary 
rather  to  organise  that  competition  than  to  seek  to 
establish  an  agreement.  The  struggle  for  existence 
is  a  well-known  fact  of  our  own  days,  but  this 
struggle,  which  may  be  circumscribed  among  the 
animal  races,  does  not  prevent  a  certain  degree  of 
union  and  agreement  among  men  in  view  of  a  better 
existence.  Groups  may  be  formed  to  struggle  against 
other  groups;  the  citizens  of  one  and  the  same  nation 


SUBORDINATION  OF  THE  ECONOMIC  ORDER.  293 

may  closely  combine  in  their  economic  struggle  against 
another  nation  equally  combined.1 

The  best  part  of  humanity  in  fact  may  constitute 
itself  into  a  single  system  to  struggle  against 
animality,  and  may  attain  a  more  complete  control 
of  nature.  Evolution  takes  place  in  the  direction  of 
the  suppression  of  these  struggles  when  they  are 
narrowly  circumscribed  in  the  clan,  the  tribe,  the 
city,  the  province,  the  nation.  Civil  wars  are  already 
considered  as  anomalous.  Certain  forms  of  com- 
petition become  no  less  abnormal.  Morality  is  as 
desirable  in  economic  struggles  as  in  every  other 
sphere  of  social  life.  It  would  be  contradictory  to 
lay  down  as  a  supreme  duty  the  rational  organisation 
of  collective  life,  and  to  leave  political  economy  out- 
side morality  as  a  domain  in  which  success  alone  is 
the  important  matter,  and  in  which  the  predominant 
fact  must  be  competition,  while  everywhere  else  in 
social  life  is  established  the  free  agreement  of  indi- 
vidual wills  under  State  control  and  protection. 


143-  Subordination  of  the  Economic  Order  to 
a  Higher  Order. 

Immorality  consists  in  the  forgetting  of  the 
highest  needs  of  human  society,  and  in  the  exclusive 
subordination  of  man  to  economic  ends,  such  as  the 
acquisition  of  wealth  or  the  production  of  means  of 
pleasure.  The  Kantians  see  in  this  abuse  of  human 

1  Protectionists  such  as  Mr.  Simon  Patten  may  look  forward  to  this. 
To  them  the  aim  of  Protection  is  the  full  expansion  of  the  whole 
economic  power  of  a  nation  which  is  called  into  rivalry  with  its 
neighbours.  Cf.  The  Economic  Basis  of  Protection. 


294  THE    ECONOMICAL    ORGANISATION. 

weakness  the  sign  of  a  tendency  to  take  humanity  in 
itself  as  a  means  and  not  an  end,  not  to  respect  the 
law  of  duty  and  the  noumenal  liberty  in  the  pheno- 
menal being  whose  "eminent  dignity"  and  funda- 
mental autonomy  do  not  tolerate  subjection. 

We  may  not  have  metaphysical  reasons  for  con- 
demning the  occasional  degradation  of  reasonable 
beings,  lowered  to  the  rank  of  beasts  of  burden,  or 
treated  as  mere  instruments  of  labour.  Reasons 
borrowed  from  positive  morality  do  not  fail  to  justify 
the  condemnation  of  slavery  and  of  analogous  modes 
of  social  activity.  There  is  in  society  a  hierarchy  of 
different  orders.  The  order  of  economic  facts  is  un- 
doubtedly at  the  base  as  the  first  condition  of  other 
orders  of  facts — political,  aesthetic,  scientific,  and  so 
on.  If  man  does  not  live  by  bread  alone,  he  must  at 
least  begin  by  being  nourished,  dressed,  and  aided  in 
his  primary  wants  and  self-preservation.  Moreover, 
it  cannot  fairly  be  claimed  that  economic  evolution 
determines  the  whole  of  social  evolution.  The 
doctrine  of  "historical  materialism"  has  certainly 
insisted  too  much  on  economic  determinism.  As 
may  be  seen  by  what  has  been  said  above,  the 
evolution  of  the  means  of  production  has  in  many 
cases  followed  that  of  the  spontaneous  tendencies, 
and  of  the  desires  that  any  "material  want"  has 
awakened.  The  complexity  of  economic  life  has 
political,  aesthetic,  religious,  and  social  causes  of 
every  kind  outside  the  natural  evolution  of  the 
sources  of  wealth.  But  the  inventions  which  con- 
tribute to  industrial  progress  are  not  in  their  origin 
products  of  the  human  mind  under  the  pressure  of 
economic  necessity.  They  are  the  spontaneous  fruit 
of  technical  imagination,  the  direct  results  of  the 


SUBORDINATION  OF  THE  ECONOMIC  ORDER.  295 

most  disinterested  scientific  research.  It  may  be 
asserted  that  in  many  cases  artistic  or  scientific 
disinterestedness  has  given  rise  to  economic  interests. 

We  must  let  the  order  of  scientific  facts  play  its  part, 
which  is  extremely  important  although  subordinate — 
that  of  the  totality  of  conditioned  and  conditioning 
phenomena,  but  conditioning  after  the  fashion  of  the 
pedestal  in  granite  or  marble  which  is  necessary  for 
the  erection  of  a  statue.  The  phenomena  of  wealth, 
of  production,  of  consumption,  and  of  distribution 
are  means  for  the  social  life ;  we  must  not  make  ends 
of  them,  and  thereby  enslave  either  individuals  or 
communities.  This  is  the  pitfall  which  most  econo- 
mists have  not  avoided  with  sufficient  care. 

The  wealth  of  individuals  or  nations  is  in  itself  a 
matter  of  indifference  to  the  moralist.  Wealth  or 
poverty  do  not  increase  or  decrease  morality.  There 
are  certain  wealthy  regions  in  which,  in  spite  of  a 
marked  propensity  to  vices  such  as  avarice  or 
debauchery,  crime  does  not  increase  more  than  in 
poor  regions  in  which  are  developed  vices  such  as 
intemperance,  ignorance,  coarseness  of  manners,  etc. 
In  general,  very  poor  populations  have  more  virtues 
than  populations  which  are  weakened  by  wealth 
and  habituated  to  luxury.  Poverty  endured  with 
fortitude  is  a  test  of  morality.  But  the  possession 
of  a  fortune  interests  morality  indirectly  in  so  far 
as  it  should  serve  as  a  means  of  social  activity. 
Certain  forms  of  good  increase  the  public  means 
of  arriving  at  scientific  truth,  artistic  enjoyment,  or 
the  full  expansion  of  charitable  forces.  The  moral 
use  of  wealth  is  the  expenditure  of  its  revenues  for 
more  and  more  lofty  social  work.  It  is  of  importance 
therefore  that  the  public  wealth  should  increase,  that 


2g6  THE    ECONOMICAL    ORGANISATION. 

humanity  should  possess  an  increasing  quantity  of 
material  good,  in  order  that  the  intellectual  and 
moral  life  of  the  community  may  benefit  by  the 
leisure  and  the  resources  so  widely  distributed.  But 
if  this  be  the  case,  what  moral  importance  is  acquired 
by  the  problem  of  the  production  and  distribution  of 
wealth !  How  closely  is  political  economy  sub- 
ordinated to  morality ! 

Now,  if  there  is  a  natural  evolution  to  promote,  if 
there  are  reforms  to  be  realised,  it  is  to  the  law  that 
we  must  appeal  in  the  widest  measure  possible;  it  is 
the  State  which  must  assume  new  duties  and  arro- 
gate to  itself  new  rights. 

144.  The  Role  of  the  State. 

Let  us  remain  faithful  to  the  fundamental  prin- 
ciples which  limit  the  rights  of  the  sovereign  in 
private  matters,  the  principle  of  the  greatest  possible 
expansion  of  individual  liberty  hand  in  hand  with 
that  of  State  control  and  protection,  and  the  prin- 
ciple of  co-ordination  and  prevision  by  the  central 
power,  in  view  of  the  progressive  realisation  of  an 
ideal  of  harmony  and  spontaneous  agreement 
between  social  forces  of  the  most  diverse  character. 
The  role  of  the  State  then  clearly  appears  to  be  that 
of  a  power  which  promotes  the  economical  evolution 
of  which  we  have  already  marked  out  the  stages.  In 
proportion  as  the  division  of  labour  daily  involves,  in 
a  manner  more  and  more  marked,  the  triumph  of 
special  aptitudes,  we  see  the  working  classes  unite 
for  self-perfection,  and  endeavour  to  form  in  the  same 
industrial  establishment  a  great  family,  in  which 
each  needs  all,  and  in  which  all  hold  in  just  esteem 


THE    STATE    PRINCIPLE    AND    THE    CORVEE.     297 

the  part  that  is  played  by  each.  Thus  is  realised 
progressively  the  solidarity  of  the  working  classes, 
a  solidarity  from  which  we  may  expect  the  greatest 
good  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  protection  of  the 
individual,  of  encouragement  of  the  inventor,  and 
of  aid  in  case  of  the  artisan  who  is  out  of  work  or 
suffering  from  illness. 

The  extension  of  the  role  which  has  devolved  on 
the  unions,  within  the  limits  which  have  been  laid 
down  above,  is  desirable  and  even  necessary.  With- 
out granting  privileges  and  monopolies  which  would 
tend  to  turn  all  unions  into  new  corporations  as 
detestable  as  the  old,  the  State  can  and  ought  to 
favour  every  group  which  may  assist  it  as  auxiliaries 
in  the  work  of  the  economic  organisation  of  the 
country.  These  associations  will  be  able  in  pro- 
portion as  they  acquire  more  power  to  realise  vaster 
designs  and  to  give  more  breadth  to  industrial  enter- 
prise, and  at  the  same  time  to  increase  the  public 
wealth  and  the  well-being  of  all  their  members. 

145.  The  State  Principle  and  the  Corvee. 

Ought  the  State  to  go  further  and  become  a 
kind  of  magnified  union,  the  sole  proprietor,  the 
sole  distributor  of  work  and  property,  a  kind  of 
Providence  which  provides  for  the  needs  of  all  by 
fixing  the  nature  and  the  duration  of  the  labour  of 
each  ? 

Suppose  \ve  admit  that  if  men  all  work  a  few 
hours  a  day  at  the  production  of  objects  of  con- 
sumption which  are  indispensable  to  material  life ; 
all  men  may  then  be  able  to  enjoy  leisure,  which 
some  may  employ  in  scientific  research,  others  in 


298  THE    ECONOMICAL   ORGANISATION. 

works  of  art,  and  all  in  the  satisfaction  of  higher  and 
properly  human  needs, — granted  this,  has  not  the 
State  the  right  of  imposing  without  exception  on  its 
different  elements  what  has  sometimes  been  called 
the  corvee  ? 

The  right  of  imposing  defined  modes  of  activity 
with  a  view  to  the  public  safety,  or  welfare,  or 
health,  or  universal  morality,  is  incontestable.  It 
has  been  in  fact  affirmed  on  many  occasions.  The 
State  exacts  its  corvee  whenever  no  remunerated 
service  can  fulfil  the  functions  accomplished  by  all 
with  complete  devotion  to  the  State :  for  example 
in  case  of  fire,  inundation,  famine,  or  invasion. 
Military  service  is  the  type  of  the  corvee  which  is 
commended  by  many  socialists.1 

If  it  were  proved  that  social  morality  and  the 
collective  well-being  would  gain  in  realisation  by 
the  process  which  answers  to  the  need  of  national 
defence  and  of  all  work  that  the  material  exist- 
ence of  the  nation  requires,  the  State  would  not 
hesitate  to  "  nationalise "  the  principal  means  of 
production,  and  those  great  enterprises  which  have 
hitherto  remained  in  private  hands,  and  which 
have  been  denounced  as  a  tax  on  the  public  wealth 
or  harmful  to  the  physical  and  moral  health  of  all 
the  citizens. 

But  if  Plato  could  conceive  of  the  State  as 
charged,  first  with  the  union,  then  with  the  entire 
education,  and  finally  with  the  distribution  to  all  the 
citizens  of  functions  and  property,  we  must  not  for- 

1  It  must  be  remembered  that  M.  G.  Renard  reduces  to  a  minimum, 
in  his  Regime  socialiste  (Alcan,  1898),  the  part  played  by  these  indus- 
trial services,  which,  he  says,  "  would  be  secured  by  a  process  analogous 
to  that  of  military  service." 


THE    STATE    PRINCIPLE    AND    THE    CORVEE.      299 

get  that  he  over-simplified  economic  life,  which  in  his 
day  was  anything  but  complex,  and  that  he  was  in- 
spired much  more  by  the  remote  past  than  by  social 
evolution  as  a  whole.  Human  civilisation  began 
with  a  very  rudimentary  kind  of  communism. 
Social  homogeneity,  the  common  possession  of 
objects  of  consumption  and  means  of  production, 
some  reduced  to  products,  others  to  the  simplest 
modes  of  activity,  made  a  common  life  easy  and 
even  obligatory.  In  our  days  the  complexity  of 
collective  existence  has  made  it  difficult  to  con- 
centrate in  the  hands  of  the  State  the  means  of 
production  and  objects  of  consumption.  Incessant 
and  varied  exchange,  by  determining  the  expansion 
of  financial  operations,  has  more  and  more  com- 
pelled the  State  to  have  recourse  to  the  method 
which  most  easily  enables  it  to  dispose  of  the 
public  revenue — viz.,  the  process  of  taxation  by 
law  and  of  expenditure  by  budget.  The  principal 
inconvenience  of  the  corvee  system  is  the  crowding 
of  individuals,  often  against  their  will,  into  manu- 
factories or  shops ;  further,  it  leaves  no  freedom 
to  the  worker,  as  though  the  real  worker  were  only 
a  piece  of  machinery  producing  at  a  fixed  rate  a 
quantity  of  determined  work.  What  is  more  im- 
portant than  the  quantity  is  the  quality,  and  that 
depends  on  skill,  and  therefore  on  interest  in 
specialisation. 

And  what  is  more  important  than  docility  and 
regularity  is  invention,  which  can  only  take  place 
by  leaving  to  the  individual  the  right  of  change, 
and  a  right  as  it  were  to  make  mistakes,  to  make 
experiments,  and  a  right  to  consumption  that  may 
possibly  be  fruitless. 


300  THE    ECONOMICAL   ORGANISATION. 

146.  Taxation. 

On  the  other  hand,  the  system  of  taxes  leaves  to 
the  producer  and  the  consumer  the  maximum  of 
liberty,  while  it  permits  the  State  to  play  the 
broadest  role  that  can  be  conceived.  We  ought, 
therefore,  to  foresee  and  to  admit  a  continued 
increase  in  the  pecuniary  burdens  imposed  upon 
individuals  as  the  consequence  of  a  continuous 
expansion  of  the  role  which  has  devolved  on  the 
central  power. 

Social  evolution  may  rightly  tend  to  make  each 
citizen  according  to  his  individual  competence  a 
functionary  of  the  State.  To  the  regime  of  com- 
petition corresponds  the  selection  by  competition 
of  agents  who  are  supposed  to  be  the  fittest  to 
render  services  which  are  sometimes  very  complex. 
To  the  regime  of  co-operation  should  correspond 
the  breaking  up  of  the  present  great  functions  into 
small  and  much  more  specialised  functions,  re- 
munerated in  each  case  according  to  the  aptitude 
of  the  individual  to  fulfil  the  duty  assigned  to  him. 
The  time  will  thus  come  when  there  will  be  no 
longer  only  a  limited  number  of  citizens  who  are 
exclusively  State  functionaries,  and  when  all  citizens 
will  be  more  or  less  such  officials  for  a  few  hours 
a  day,  or  for  a  small  portion  of  their  activity.  In 
that  case  the  State  will  have  not  so  much  to  feed 
its  employes  as  to  remunerate  their  services,  to 
exchange  with  each  citizen  the  means  of  subsist- 
ence in  return  for  those  products  which  are  in- 
dispensable to  the  collective  life. 

Two  practical  problems  will  therefore  be  pre- 
sented. How  shall  we  redistribute  the  taxes,  and 


SOLIDARITY    IN    THE    ECONOMIC    ORDER.         301 

how  far  can  we  make  private  enterprises  public  ? 
The  latter  problem  may  be  solved  in  a  variety  of 
ways  according  to  the  degree  of  civilisation  and  the 
economic  situation.  At  the  present  moment  a  large 
number  of  States  have  already  taken  under  their 
charge  a  portion  of  the  expense  of  public  instruc- 
tion, a  portion  of  the  expenses  of  assistance  to  the 
sick  and  the  old,  and  the  protection  and  material 
maintenance  of  poor  children  or  foundlings.  We 
constantly  see  our  Parliaments  increasing  their 
subsidies  and  making  fresh  sacrifices  to  secure, 
for  example,  cheap  transport  or  certain  articles  of 
cheap  food ;  on  the  other  hand,  we  see  great  nations 
paying  very  high  prices  to  encourage  certain  forms 
of  cultivation,  navigation,  emigration,  etc.,  thus 
improving  the  condition  of  the  farmers,  sailors,  and 
colonists.  The  fact  that  an  enterprise  is  of  public 
utility  is  sufficient  reason  for  the  State  to  intervene 
pecuniarily  and  morally,  and  to  partly  nationalise 
it  by  the  aid  of  taxes.  It  is  certainly  not  immoral 
to  turn  in  this  fashion  every  great  enterprise,  which 
is  now  private  and  of  capital  importance  to  the 
national  life,  into  a  public  concern,  and  thereby  to 
cheapen  the  means  which  are  indispensable  to  the 
subsistence  of  all.  It  secures  for  all,  by  means  of  the 
public  funds,  at  any  rate  assistance  against  poverty. 
It  enables  all  to  raise  themselves  more  and  more 
above  the  life  of  the  brutes,  and  to  taste  of  those 
intellectual  and  aesthetic  pleasures  which  ennoble 
mankind. 

147.  Solidarity  in  the  Economic  Order. 

For  this  purpose  all  must  sacrifice  to  the  State  a 
portion  of  their  income.     And  it  is  exactly  in  the 


302  THE    ECONOMICAL    ORGANISATION. 

variable  relations  between  the  benefits  received  by 
the  individual  from  society  and  the  services  rendered 
by  him  to  the  common  cause  that  human  solidarity 
can  best  be  manifested.  These  relations  most  often 
run  the  risk  of  being  in  inverse  proportion.  In  fact,  it 
is  not  the  man  who  is  powerful  by  his  intellect,  by  his 
ability  from  this  or  that  point  of  view,  wrho  will  have 
most  need  of  the  aid  of  his  fellows;  but,  qua  abler 
man,  it  is  only  moral  that  he  should  owe  more,  and 
that  the  social  burdens  which  weigh  upon  him 
should  be  proportional  to  his  means  of  action. 
We  have  seen,  in  fact,  that  as  duty  rests  on  good- 
will, social  obligations  increase  with  the  growth  of 
power.  To  pay  a  tax  is  one  of  these  obligations; 
and  even  if  it  be  true,  as  we  have  often  supposed, 
that  the  tax  will  more  and  more  take  the  place 
of  all  individual  contributions  to  the  collective 
charges  that  may  be  exacted  by  the  State,  we  must 
see  in  the  payment  of  the  pecuniary  contribution 
one  of  the  first  duties  of  the  citizen,  a  duty  the 
higher  in  the  hierarchy  of  moral  obligations  in  pro- 
portion as  the  economic  role  of  the  State  becomes 
greater. 

One  serious  objection  cannot  fail  to  be  raised  to 
such  a  conception.  It  is,  that  if  the  advantages  are 
not  proportional  to  the  services  rendered,  if  on  the 
other  hand  the  idlest  and  most  unworthy  of  men 
none  the  less  enjoy  the  benefit  of  the  labour  of 
others,  a  kind  of  premium  will  be  given  to  inaction, 
idleness  may  become  general,  and  the  social  system 
may  collapse  as  a  natural  consequence. 

If  the  objection  hold  good,  it  follows  that  the  only 
things  that  determine  man  to  work  are  natural 
necessities  and  economic  needs.  Now  we  have 


SOLIDARITY    IN    THE    ECONOMIC    ORDER.         303 

already  seen  the  exaggeration  in  the  doctrine  that 
claims  to  make  of  material  needs  the  sole  motives  of 
human  activity.  On  the  other  hand,  do  we  not  daily 
see  that  the  laziness  of  certain  men  is  due  to  their 
morbid  disposition,  such  that  even  if  hunger  and 
thirst  were  to  prove  a  still  more  powerful  stimu- 
lant to  labour,  they  would  nevertheless  remain  idle  ? 
Is  it  not  true,  on  the  contrary,  that  a  large  number 
of  men  work  who  need  not ;  and  can  we  believe  that 
inventors,  for  instance,  the  great  agents  of  industrial 
progress  and  economic  prosperity,  would  cease  to 
imagine,  to  study,  or  to  make  an  effort,  even  if  they 
were  deprived  of  all  material  recompense  ?  It  is 
laying  too  much  stress  on  the  baseness  of  the 
sentiments  of  the  majority  of  men  to  think  that  the 
cause  of  civilisation  is  compromised  because  bread 
and  shelter  have  been  secured  to  a  few  wretches  with 
no  self-respect.  There  is  nothing  which  entitles  us 
to  believe  that  once  the  most  urgent  necessities  of 
material  existence  are  provided  for  as  far  as  possible 
by  the  care  of  the  State,  the  individual  would  not 
consider  it  a  point  of  honour  to  give  back  to  the 
community  the  benefits  which  he  has  received  from 
it.  Thus,  on  the  contrary,  an  incomparable  intel- 
lectual impulse  and  an  incomparable  economic 
activity  will  instil  into  the  community  an  increasing 
solicitude  for  all  its  members,  and  will  secure  for 
individuals  wider  and  more  generous  action,  more 
fertile  initiative,  greater  wealth,  and  a  well-being 
which  will  always  be  favourable  to  their  moral 
elevation.  Without  prejudice  to  private  property, 
the  problem  of  the  conflict  between  labour  and 
capital  will  be  made  easier  by  the  amelioration  of 
the  lot  of  the  lowly. 


304  THE    ECONOMICAL    ORGANISATION. 

148.  The  Wages  System. 

Karl  Marx1  has  endeavoured  to  establish  a  filial 
relationship  between  ancient  slavery,  modern  serf- 
dom, and  the  wages  system.  In  reality,  serfdom 
from  its  origin  is  opposed  to  slavery,  and  the  wages 
system  has  been  received  with  enthusiasm  by  the 
adversaries  of  serfdom.  As  Letourneau  has  re- 
marked, these  institutions  co-existed  in  Egypt  and 
Greece  without  causing  confusion ;  in  Sweden, 
according  to  Dareste,  serfdom  has  never  existed. 
The  artisan,  once  so  despised  that  he  was  not  only 
refused  the  title  of  citizen  but  also  every  moral 
dignity,  tends  more  and  more  to  become  an  inde- 
pendent personality  even  from  the  economical  point 
of  view. 

The  wages  system,  which  is  nowadays  so 
vehemently  attacked,  is  condemned  to  disappear 
because  it  does  not  leave  room  for  the  moral  evo- 
lution of  the  artisan.  In  law,  wages  is  the  result  of 
a  contract,  by  which  a  man  engages  to  furnish  a 
determined  technical  activity  for  a  certain  number  of 
hours  a  day  to  a  master,  who,  in  return,  engages  to 
procure  for  him  certain  material  advantages,  generally 
a  certain  sum  of  money. 

But  as  a  matter  of  fact  the  regime  of  the  wages 
system  is  often  in  opposition  to  the  regime  of  free 
contract.  The  conditions  under  which  the  workman 
engages  to  work  for  his  master  are  often  imposed  by 
the  latter,  who,  in  union  with  most  other  masters,  or 
at  any  rate  in  consequence  of  a  tacit  understanding, 
does  not  stop  to  discuss  the  matter  with  the  work- 

1  Capital,  p.  550.  — TR. 


THE   WAGES    SYSTEM.  305 

man ;  and  the  workman,  if  he  is  not  to  die  of  hunger, 
must  certainly  accept  the  offer. 

On  the  other  hand,  it  sometimes  happens  that  the 
members  of  a  union  impose  their  price  on  the  master, 
and  being  certain  of  success,  have  not  to  fight  but 
to  command.  It  follows,  therefore,  that  the  wages 
system  perpetuates  a  state  of  war. 

And  there  is  a  still  more  serious  matter.  Is  not 
the  contract  of  the  wages  system  a  contract  of  hire, 
which  makes  of  the  workman  a  thing,  a  tool,  a 
simple  means  of  wealth  in  the  hands  of  the 
capitalist  ?  If  we  consider  facts  and  history,  says 
M.  Renouvier,1  the  wage-earners  incontestably  "  have 
been  placed  and  often  even  now  are  placed  in  a  con- 
dition in  which  not  only  can  they  have  no  property 
of  their  own,  but  they  are  unable  to  acquire  any. 
They  find  themselves  reduced  to  the  bare  means  of 
livelihood  from  day  to  day,  and  so  are  shut  off  from 
all  more  remote  ends  whether  of  an  intellectual  or 
of  a  moral  nature." 

We  know  Karl  Marx's2  theory  of  surplus-value  and 
over-production.  Into  the  prices  at  which  goods  are 
sold  enter  essentially  the  wages  of  the  workmen  and 
the  profit  of  the  master.  This  profit  is  due  to  over- 
production— that  is  to  say,  to  the  hours  of  "  unpaid  " 
work  which  are  imposed  on  the  workman  beyond  the 
number  of  hours  that  are  necessary  for  the  needs  of 
society. 

The  capitalist  endeavours  to  increase  the  surplus- 
value  which  results  from  the  incorporation  into  his 
goods  of  an  ever-increasing  number  of  hours  of  work, 
and  of  an  ever  more  considerable  amount  of  effective 

1  Op.  <•//.,  t.  ii.  p.  86. 

2  "Salaries,  Prices,  and  Profits,"  Capital,  pp.  156-300,  516-541. -Tk. 

20 


306  THE    ECONOMICAL    ORGANISATION. 

work.  It  follows  that,  even  without  decrease  of 
wages,  the  profits  of  the  masters  increase  to  the 
detriment  of  their  men,  and  that  life  which  becomes 
more  costly  to  the  consumers  is  more  costly  to  the 
wrorking  classes  generally,  so  that  a  rise  in  wages 
does  not  improve  their  condition. 

The  morality  of  a  few  masters  can  do  nothing 
against  these  inevitable  consequences  of  the  wages 
system.  If  they  were  to  increase  wages,  or  to  reduce 
the  number  of  hours  of  work,  they  would  be  ruined 
by  the  severity  of  competition. 

149.  Co-operation. 

The  State  is  therefore  sooner  or  later  called  upon 
to  intervene  in  the  present  regime  of  labour,  to  fix 
the  judicial  limits  within  which  may  be  exercised 
that  individual  right  of  contract  without  injury  to 
the  moral  dignity  of  the  human  person  affected. 
The  regulation  of  labour,  notably  with  respect  to  the 
maximum  hours  of  labour  and  the  minimum  wage, 
must  therefore  be  imposed  upon  the  State. 

This  is  the  modern  thesis  which  rightly  assigns 
to  the  State  the  regulative  function  which  is  dis- 
tinctly proper  to  it.  But  can  it  be  expected  that 
State  regulation  will  be  sufficient  to  give  to  the 
working  man  adequate  moral  dignity  ?  It  seems 
that  there  can  be  no  moral  satisfaction  to  humanity 
until  social  labour  as  a  whole  appears  as  free  co- 
operation, in  which  no  material  or  moral  compulsion 
is  exercised  by  one  set  of  men  on  another  in  virtue 
of  the  power  of  the  one  and  the  weakness  of  the 
other. 

It  is  not  a  case  of  hiring  the  activity  of  an.~indi- 


CO-OPERATION.  307 

vidual ;  it  is  rather  a  case  of  services  which  should  be 
exchanged  between  men  having  an  equal  respect  the 
one  for  the  other,  and  a  reciprocal  esteem  for  their 
different  aptitudes.  The  division  of  labour  involves, 
in  addition  to  the  increasing  specialisation  of  apti- 
tudes and  an  increasing  individual  value,  the  more 
and  more  marked  independence  of  the  good  workman 
who  works  at  his  ease,  sells  his  labour  or  his  services, 
and  receives,  not  the  price  of  his  hours  of  labour,  but 
the  share  that  is  due  to  his  talent,  his  knowledge,  his 
skill,  and  his  co-operation  in  a  piece  of  work. 

How  much  better  would  the  legitimate  pride  of  a 
good  workman  and  his  independence  with  regard  to 
the  master  be  secured  in  a  society  in  which,  in  the 
first  place,  free  association  would  furnish  to  the  indi- 
vidual every  moral  and  pecuniary  support,  and  in 
which  the  State  wTould  afterwards  assure  to  all  a  life 
free  from  pecuniary  anxiety.  It  is  not  a  question  of 
repeating  the  blunders  of  1848  and  1849,  and  of 
opening  national  workshops  for  men  who  are  out 
of  work.  The  State  cannot  engage  to  find  a  liveli- 
hood for  a  swarm  of  officials,  who,  if  they  did  not 
work  w^ould  compromise  the  public  weal,  and  if  they 
did  work  would  cause  such  a  competition  with  private 
industry  that  it  would  be  unjustly  condemned  and 
would  have  to  disappear.  But  the  workman  with  a 
family,  wife,  parents,  and  children  to  feed  and  to 
bring  up,  both  must  and  can,  if  need  be,  struggle  in 
defence  of  his  legitimate  claims  against  the  some- 
times overwhelming  power  of  capital.  Should  he 
claim  in  case  of  need  his  rights  and  those  of  his 
companions,  the  conditions  under  which  his  claim  is 
made  are  the  most  favourable  if  his  subsistence  has 
been  made  as  cheap  as  possible  to  him,  and  if  the 


308  THE    ECONOMICAL    ORGANISATION. 

material  well-being  assured  to  all  by  the  State  has 
enabled  him  to  save  and  to  protect  himself  in  advance 
by  far-sighted  economy. 

We  may  rest  assured  that  under  such  conditions 
the  right  of  striking — which  must  be  recognised,  for 
it  is  the  guarantee  of  the  independence  of  the  work- 
ing classes — would  be  exercised  peacefully;  the  fear 
of  poverty,  of  being  a  short  time  out  of  work,  is  the 
cause  of  most  acts  of  violence  committed  in  the  con- 
flicts of  labour;  it  is  this  fear  that  maddens  and 
blinds.  When  a  powerful  union  maintains  its  mem- 
bers, who  are  already  strong  in  themselves,  the 
solution  is  easy  and  rapid.  We  see  this  in  England 
where  the  trades  unions  constitute  an  economic 
organ  of  the  highest  importance. 

150.  The  Work  of  Women  and  Children. 

In  the  same  way,  thanks  to  such  an  organisation, 
we  might  lessen  the  effects  of  the  general  tendency 
to  the  employment  of  women  and  children,  in  so  far 
as  that  tendency  is  reconcilable  with  a  healthy  social 
organisation.  No  doubt  woman  can  play,  and  ought 
to  play,  a  role  of  more  and  more  importance  in  political 
economy,  and  she  may  contribute"  to  the  material 
prosperity  of  a  country  by  work  which  is  pro- 
portioned to  her  strength,  and  which  corresponds 
to  her  aptitudes;  but  she  cannot  without  serious 
inconvenience  desert  the  domestic  hearth,  abandon 
her  children,  and  be  compelled  to  devote  herself  to 
continuous  labour  which  removes  her  from  the  cares 
of  the  household,  and  to  a  fatiguing  toil  which  is 
harmful  to  the  exercise  of  her  natural  function — 
maternity.  As  for  the  child,  it  cannot  be  employed 


THE    VALUE    OF   THE    WORKMAN.  309 

at  an  early  age  except  to  the  detriment  of  its 
instruction,  its  education,  its  physical  and  moral 
development,  and  its  technical  value.  The  society 
which  cannot  prevent  the  excessive  labour,  prolonged 
or  premature,  of  women  and  children  is  not  a  morally 
organised  society. 


151.  The  Value  of  the  Workman. 

In  a  community  in  which  wealth  is  distributed 
according  to  social  value,  in  which  the  worker  is  not 
compelled  by  the  most  pressing  material  needs  to 
sacrifice  his  rights  and  those  of  his  wife  and  children, 
one  of  the  first  duties  of  every  man  is  to  acquire  his 
proper  technical  value. 

Since  a  social  system  must  be  realised,  no  one  has 
the  right  to  consider  himself  as  exempt  from  working 
on  behalf  of  the  realisation  of  this  system.  The 
obligation  of  labour,  that  no  morality  but  a  social 
morality  can  demonstrate,  seems  to  me  to  be  rigor- 
ously established  by  the  rational  subordination  of 
individual  to  collective  ends,  by  the  subordination 
of  a  system  that  is  restricted  to  a  system  that  is 
wader. 

It  goes  without  saying  that  the  word  "labour" 
must  be  taken  in  its  widest  sense,  and  that  it  simply 
implies  methodic  activity  continued  with  effort  in  order 
to  realise  a  piece  of  work,  either  aesthetic,  or  of  urgent 
necessity,  whether  scientific  or  political.  Every  man 
takes  up  a  trade,  according  to  his  aptitudes  and  social 
needs.  That  the  country  requires  a  large  number  of 
farmers  or  sailors  is  not  sufficient  reason  for  imposing 
on  the  majority  of  its  inhabitants  the  profession  of 
a  farmer  or  a  seafaring  life;  and  that  is  perhaps  the 


310  THE    ECONOMICAL    ORGANISATION. 

mistake  made  by  some  collectivists  when  they  practi- 
cally ignore  individual  aptitudes  by  claiming  to  dic- 
tate to  each  individual  the  career  he  must  follow, 
according  to  the  economic  necessities  of  society. 
But,  on  the  other  hand,  if  a  man  have  an  artistic 
temperament,  that  is  no  reason  for  his  abandoning 
the  plough  or  the  pick,  the  field  or  the  mine,  and 
thus  swelling  the  ranks  of  unappreciated  painters  or 
musicians.  In  fact,  we  have  sometimes  seen  the 
liberal  professions  overcrowded  and  manual  labour 
neglected  through  our  paying  too  much  attention  to 
individual  aptitudes  and  ignoring  social  necessities. 

152.  The  Choice  of  a  Profession. 

A  man  may  therefore  fail  in  his  duty  as  a  worker 
although  he  works  with  energy  and  talent,  because 
there  has  been  developed  in  him  an  aptitude  society 
does  not  require,  while  it  claims  the  equally  possible 
development  of  other  aptitudes. 

Social  morality  therefore  enters  even  into  the 
choice  of  a  profession,  and  this  choice  requires 
both  psychological  knowledge  and  sociological  data. 
Parents  cannot  determine  the  future  of  their  child- 
ren, and  young  men  cannot  embrace  a  career 
without  the  preliminary  inquiry:  what  are  the 
necessary  aptitudes  ?  Does  the  future  worker  pos- 
sess them  ?  Will  society  need  such  services  ? 

How  useful  therefore  it  would  be  if  minute 
observations  were  taken  from  the  birth  of  the  child 
on  his  character,  his  mode  of  mental  development,  his 
tastes  both  in  the  family  and  at  school,  his  sensorial 
imaginative  and  emotional  type,  and  his  intellectual 
and  practical  capacity!  Provided  with  such  infor- 


THE    RIGHTS    AND    DUTIES    OF   THE    WORKMAN.    311 

mation,  the  psychologist  would  be  in  a  position  to 
pronounce  an  opinion  on  the  value  of  the  pro- 
fessional choice  made  by  the  young  man  or  by  his 
family.1 

Then  the  sociologist  would  appear  on  the  scene. 
In  most  cases  his  place  might  be  taken  by  any 
judicious  observer,  who,  for  instance,  foreseeing  the 
development  of  a  taste  for  architecture  or  an  interest 
in  agriculture,  would  advise  the  would-be  artist  to  be 
an  architect  rather  than  a  painter,  and  the  would-be 
artisan  to  take  up  an  agricultural  rather  than  an 
industrial  career. 


153.  The  Rights  and  Duties  of  the  Workman. 

A  choice  made  with  discrimination  is  the  most 
likely  to  be  completely  moral.  Immediately  it  is 
made  it  involves  rights  for  him  who  accepts  the 
obligation  of  working  with  determination  at  the  real- 
isation of  the  social  system.  So  far,  the  child  had 
a  right  only  to  the  general  education  and  instruction 
which  might  adapt  him  to  the  special  education  and 
instruction  which  he  must  henceforth  receive.  But 
the  right  to  apprenticeship  results  from  the  duty  of 
learning  and  of  specialising,  a  duty  which  itself 
results  from  the  sociological  law  of  the  division  of 
labour. 

This  right  devolves  on  the  family,  the  city,  and 
the  State,  and  even  on  every  more  or  less  restricted 
community  organised  in  view  of  the  accomplishment 
of  a  definite  social  function — such  as,  for  example,  a 
union  or  a  corporation. 

1  Gallon's  Life  History  Album  (Macmillnn)  will  be  found  to  facilitate? 
the  record  of  such  observations, — TK, 


312  THE    ECONOMICAL    ORGANISATION. 

It  is  right  that  the  obligation  to  give  the  young  a 
professional  education  should  be  divided  between 
each  of  these  social  groups.  In  general,  the  family 
may  assist  apprenticeship  rather  than  give  it  directly. 
The  city  and  the  State  may  prepare  for  it  very 
satisfactorily,  or  may  complete  it  by  professional 
schools;  but  it  is  especially  to  the  associations  of 
trades,  the  guardians  of  traditions,  the  depositories 
of  ancient  precepts  as  well  as  of  recent  innovations, 
by  which  is  affirmed  the  continuity  of  human  effort 
in  a  determined  direction  and  on  a  definite  point  of 
laborious  activity — it  is  especially  to  these  modern 
unions,  for  which  the  most  brilliant  future  is  on  all 
sides  predicted,  and  which  we  hope  will  render  the 
same  services  as  the  ancient  corporations  without 
reviving  their  abuses — it  is  to  these  that  we  look 
for  the  ultimate  formation  of  the  aptitudes  of  the 
worker. 

The  master  who  nowadays  undertakes  the  duty  of 
forming  a  workman  substitutes  himself  for  the  whole 
body  of  the  trade  of  which  he  is  sometimes  but  a 
secondary  element ;  he  is  not  always  adapted  to  the 
accomplishment  of  the  task  that  he  undertakes,  and 
often  misconceives  the  extent  of  his  duties.  He  has 
a  right  to  the  obedience,  the  respect,  and  the  grati- 
tude of  his  apprentice,  and  to  the  gratitude  of  his 
fellow-citizens;  but  only  so  far  as  he  has  the  power 
and  the  will  to  bring  into  society  a  new  factor  of 
prosperity  or  happiness. 

On  the  other  hand,  the  workman  with  respect  to 
whom  society  has  fulfilled  its  duties  of  general  and 
technical  education  has  a  right  to  consideration,  only 
so  far  as  he  is  prepared  to  furnish  to  society  a  factor 
of  progress.  It  follows  that  it  is  his  duty  to  make 


THE    RIGHTS   AND    DUTIES    OF   THE    WORKMAN.    313 

himself  acquainted  with  everything  connected  with 
his  trade,  and  to  bring  into  it  that  spirit  of  discipline 
and  of  independence  which  permits  of  social  reforms 
and  valuable  inventions. 

As  for  the  workman  with  respect  to  whom  society 
has  fulfilled  all  its  duties  of  protection,  by  furnishing 
him  in  free  association  defensive  weapons  against 
every  form  of  abuse,  against  poverty,  against  disease, 
and  against  the  despotism  of  the  capitalist,  is  it  not 
his  duty  to  strengthen  in  his  turn  a  beneficent 
organisation  and  to  develop  the  moral  and  material 
power  of  his  association  or  of  his  union  ?  Can  he 
rest  content  with  an  increase  in  his  personal  comfort 
while  ignoring  his  duties  with  respect  to  the  collective 
wealth  and  the  common  honour  ? 

We  have  seen  how  the  evolution  of  the  forms  of 
property  tends  to  the  expansion  of  individual  pro- 
perty, both  real  and  personal.  This  tendency  has 
been  legalised  by  general  considerations  and  affirmed 
by  a  comprehensive  conception  of  a  social  ideal.  It 
is  the  same  with  the  tendency  of  certain  communities, 
professional  unions,  or  other  groups  having  for  their 
end  the  realisation  of  a  common  economical  aim. 
The  extension  of  collective  property,  which  is  the 
object  of  this  tendency,  is  desirable  in  order  to  give 
material  support  to  professional  solidarity,  in  order 
to  realise  more  completely  the  community  of  interests 
of  the  workmen.  The  individual  therefore  must 
labour  at  the  development  of  the  general  wealth, 
and  he  or  his  fellows  must  furnish  to  his  group  the 
best  means  of  defence  and  support. 


314  THE    FAMILY,    FRIENDSHIP,    ETC. 


VII. 


THE  FAMILY,  FRIENDSHIP,  AND  THE  COLLECTIVE 
SENTIMENTS. 

154.  The  Rights  of  Woman. 

FAMILY  evolution  seemed  opposed  to  the  spirit  of 
authority  which  dominated  the  constitution  of  the 
ancient  family ;  hence  the  expression,  the  "  dis- 
solution of  the  family"  so  frequently  employed  to 
indicate  a  future  which  did  not  so  much  involve 
the  ruin  of  the  family  as  the  decadence  of  what  had 
appeared  to  be  its  fundamental  principle — the  power 
of  the  chief. 

Ought  morality  to  teach  woman  blind  obedience 
and  unconditional  submission  to  her  husband  ? 
Here  it  seems  that  the  title  of  citizen  or  repre- 
sentative of  the  State,  and  therefore  of  law  and 
reason  in  the  family  community,  can  be  bestowed 
on  man  alone.  He  has  responsibilities,  and  he  has 
duties  of  the  most  varied  nature.  The  wife,  on 
the  other  hand,  has  the  most  peaceful  possible  life; 
she  seems  to  have  no  right  to  anything  but  to 
protection. 

However,  the  difference  between  the  faculties  of 
the  man  and  of  the  woman  is  not  so  great  that  we 
can  assert  that  the  subordination  of  the  one  sex  to 
the  other  is  necessary  in  the  future.  "  We  do  not 
dispute,"  says  M.  Renouvier,  and  rightly,  "  that 
many  men  are  inferior  to  many  women  on  the  very 
points  in  which  we  should  say  women  are  as  a  whole 
inferior  to  men.  ...  It  is  true  that  if  the  faculties  of 
women  and  men  do  not  differ  essentially,  they  have 


THE    RIGHTS    OF   WOMAN.  315 

functions  which  are  naturally  diverse.  It  does  not 
follow  that  woman  may  be  deprived  of  her  right  as 
a  reasonable  being  to  determine  her  own  choice  and 
to  proceed  freely  in  her  own  autonomy."  M.  J. 
Lourbet l  asserts  that  "  the  apparent  inferiority  of 
woman  is  accidental,  provisional,  and  external  in 
the  indefinite  evolution  of  humanity,  this  inferiority 
having  its  principle  in  the  physical  minority." 

We  know  that  Lombroso  and  Ferrero2  have  not 
hesitated  to  admit  that  there  are  natural  tendencies 
to  immorality  in  both  women  and  children.  Love  of 
children  is  the  predominant  characteristic  of  the  sex. 
It  manifests  itself  not  only  in  the  nervous,  muscular, 
and  bony  systems,  but  also  in  all  the  other  functions — 
circulation,  respiration,  secretions,  etc.  The  mater- 
nal function  injures  the  intellectual  development. 
"  Intelligence  varies  in  inverse  ratio  to  fecundity." 
Woman  is  inferior  to  man  from  the  point  of  view 
of  the  development  of  the  sentiments.  If  she  is  more 
irritable,  more  demonstrative,  and  more  accessible  to 
the  contagion  which  causes  the  collective  emotions, 
pain  and  joy  are  less  profound  in  her  than  in  man. 
By  a  curious  paradox  woman  is  equally  accessible 
to  cruelty  and  to  pity. 

Native  criminality  is  less  frequent  in  woman  than 
in  man:  "woman  is  an  inoffensive  demi-criminaloid." 
She  is  much  more  addicted  to  prostitution  than  to 
real  crime.  Now  prostitution  is  not  a  result  of 
degeneration.  "  Prostitution,"  says  M.  G.  Richard,3 
"  is  a  matter  of  exchange.  It  is  one  of  the  features 

1  Le  Probttme  des  Sexes.     Giard  et  Briere.     Paris,  1900. 

2  La  Femme  Criminelle  et  la  Prostitute.     Alcan,  1896  (in  part  trans- 
lated into  English  as  The  Female  Offender}. 

3  Rev.  Phil.,  1896,  t.  xlii.  p.  529. 


316  THE    FAMILY,    FRIENDSHIP,    ETC. 

of  a  type  of  society  in  which  everything  is  valued  in 
money.  It  is  an  abnormal  profession  which  has  its 
own  school,  its  inferior  degrees,  and  its  aristocracy. 
It  is  a  trade  to  which  a  child  is  too  often  dedicated 
by  its  family,  with  the  tacit  consent  of  indifferent 
authority,  especially  when  the  child  has  that  external 
beauty  which  is  rarely  found  in  degeneration."  We 
may  accept  this  opinion  of  M.  Richard,  recognising 
that  many  young  girls  having  tendencies  to  prostitu- 
tion present  the  stigmata  of  degeneration:  frequent 
mental  lack  of  balance,  and  a  remarkable  diminution 
of  lofty  sentiments,  stigmata  which  show  them  to  be 
akin  to  the  "  morally  insane."  The  establishment  of 
a  social  cause  for  prostitution  makes  us  even  agree 
with  M.  Lourbet  that  it  is  "  radically  wrong  to  draw- 
conclusions  as  to  the  woman  of  the  future  from  the 
woman  of  the  past.  Contemporary  science  cannot, 
by  any  absolutely  determined  principle,  assert  that 
woman  is  incurably  weak."  Why  should  she  have 
by  nature  less  sensibility  or  intelligence  than  man  ? 
Admitting  with  Lombroso  that  maternity  interrupts 
the  development  of  the  highest  intellectual  faculties, 
admitting  that  the  various  physiological  and  psychic 
disturbances  which  are  inevitable  in  a  wroman  may 
place  an  obstacle  in  the  way  of  normal  and  perfectly 
continuous  evolution,  it  must  be  recognised  that  the 
feminine  type  which  we  know  is — as  I  have  said  in 
my  essay  on  Mental  Instability — the  product  of  a 
social  evolution  which  is  abnormal  rather  than  a 
natural  fact,  and  not  an  immutably  inferior  type.1 

Woman  becomes  more  and  more  capable  of  work 
and  sustained  effort.  The  competition  of  the  sexes 
in  the  studio,  in  teaching,  and  in  all  the  liberal  pro-, 

1  On  all  these  questions  see  Havelock  Ellis,  Man  and  Woman. — TR. 


MARRIAGE.  317 

fessions,  is  beginning  to  be  quite  appreciable.  In 
particular,  she  brings  into  her  intellectual  activity 
qualities  of  subtlety,  penetration,  and  vivacity,  which 
in  spite  of  a  generally  well-marked  mental  instability 
make  her  assistance  in  the  work  of  civilisation  of 
increasing  value. 

No  doubt,  in  feminine  emancipation  there  is  a 
pathological  side  which  has  been  rather  hastily 
considered  by  all  those  who  consider  woman  as 
inevitably  condemned  to  ignorance,  fear,  submission, 
and  inconsistent  frivolity.  The  desertion  of  the 
home,  the  loss  of  grace,  taste,  refinement,  elegance, 
beauty,  modesty,  and  feminine  charm,  the  leaving 
of  children  to  the  care  of  hirelings,  the  neglect  of 
conjugal  duties,  and  the  hatred  of  regular  life — these 
may  be  for  a  certain  time  the  price  that  must  be 
paid  for  the  progress  realised  by  the  emancipation  of 
woman.  But  all  the  errors,  all  the  faults,  and  all  the 
new  vices  of  a  sex  which  is  boldly  endeavouring  to 
develop  itself  along  its  own  lines,  cannot  constitute 
a  proof  of  the  inaptitude  of  woman  to  be  more  and 
more  a  guide  to  herself  and  to  act  as  a  moral  person. 


155.  Marriage. 

Marriage  was  at  the  outset  based  on  violence. 
Rape  is  so  frequent  in  primitive  societies  that  many 
tribes  have  retained  symbols  of  it  in  their  matri- 
monial ceremonies.  In  our  own  days  marriage 
rarely  implies  free,  well-reasoned,  and  reflective  con- 
sent in  the  contracting  parties.  Family  traditions, 
manners  and  customs,  the  spirit  of  caste,  and  the 
tyrannical  will  of  parents,  often  make  of  the  legal 
union  a  violation  of  the  individual  right.  On  the 


3l8  THE    FAMILY,    FRIENDSHIP,    ETC. 

other  hand,  it  is  impossible  not  to  take  into  account 
the  power  of  impulses,  which  often  impel  to  acts  of 
violence,  and  make  of  fear  and  the  accomplished  fact 
the  point  of  departure  of  grave  injustice. 

However,  an  increasing  share  is  given  to  the  free 
choice  of  each,  and  new  guarantees  are  ever  being 
taken  against  the  pressure  exercised  by  the  family 
or  the  environment.  Marriage  becomes  more  and 
more  a  matter  of  contract  between  two  individuals 
of  different  sex,  who  wish  to  give  a  legal  basis  to 
their  sexual  relations,  a  legal  consequence  to  their 
union.  The  State  intervenes  in  this  contract,  as  it 
does  in  all  contracts  which  have  a  legal  value, 
in  order  to  regulate  its  essential  conditions  and  to 
assure  that  they  are  carried  out.  This  intervention 
is  the  first  guarantee  of  respect  for  the  rights  of 
woman  and  of  the  accomplishment  of  the  duties 
which  are  most  generally  imposed. 

But  it  is  hardly  possible  for  the  State  to  penetrate 
further  into  family  life,  and  to  regulate  the  petty 
details  of  existence — petty  details  into  which,  how- 
ever, either  morality  or  immorality  must  enter.  As 
M.  Renouvier  says,1  the  only  moral  conditions  in 
the  relation  of  the  sexes  are  prudence  and  temper- 
ance, "the  mutual  duty  of  justice  and  fidelity  to 
explicit  or  tacit  promises,  and  the  recognition  of 
the  duties  which  arise  as  the  consequences  of  the 
relation."  But  is  there  not  sufficient  ground  for  a 
detailed  analysis  of  those  duties  which  M.  Renouvier 
calls  duties  of  justice  ?  Do  not  they  comprise  from 
the  outset  the  duties  of  love,  which  if  they  are  not 
strictly  speaking  obligations  of  justice  are  none  the 
less  the  most  solid  foundation  of  conjugal  rights  ? 

1  0/>.  eif.,  vol.  i.  p.  573- 


MARRIAGE.  ;if) 

To  compel  a  person   to  love,  it  will  be  said,  is  a 
contradiction    in    terms.       Is    there    not    such    an 
opposition    between    the    obligation    and   the   spon- 
taneity of  love,   that  if  love  becomes  obligatory  it 
completely  disappears  ?     And  so  it  is  not  a  question 
of  obliging  one  of  two  married  people  to  love  the 
other,  but  rather  of  making  love  itself  the  indispens- 
able condition  of  moral  marriage.     No  doubt  it  will 
be  objected  that  there  are  numerous  cases  of  free, 
sincere,    profound,    and    lasting    love    following   the 
sexual   union;    but    as    nothing    is   more   uncertain 
than  the  appearance  of  such  a  sentiment,  are  we 
authorised   by   a   few   examples   of  quite   fortuitous 
conjugal  happiness  to  leave  to  chance  the  appearance 
of  one  of  its  essential  conditions,  and  to  expect  as  an 
effect  of  the  sexual  union  what  ought  to  be  its  cause  ? 
Some  philosophers — men,  too,  wrho  are  not  with"1 
out    weight — have    offered    artificial   selection   as   a 
remedy  for  what  we  call   degeneration.     Would  it 
not   be   far  better  to  leave  it  to  natural  selection, 
operating  by  the  birth  of  reciprocal   love  and  the 
adaptation    of    character    and     temperament.      No 
doubt,   if  happy  results  are  to   follow,   this  implies 
the  intervention  of  the  reason,  called  in  to  moderate 
the   ardour  of  certain  pathological  tendencies,  and 
to  bring  into  play  impulsive  feelings  and  ends  of  a 
scientific  or  moral  order.     And  besides,  this  implies 
a  profound  modification  of  the  manners  of  to-day, 
at  any  rate  in  most  civilised  countries,  where  the 
young  girl  is  kept  most  strictly  on  her  guard  with 
respect  to  young  men,  as  remote  as  possible  from 
real  life,  and  is,  theoretically  at  least,  ignorant  of  the 
part  that  she  is  called  upon  to  play  in  society. 


320  THE    FAMILY,    FRIENDSHIP,    ETC. 

156.  The  Co-education  and  Equality  of  the  Sexes.1 

Before  we  can  give  a  lofty  moral  value  to  marriage 
the  education  of  the  young  man  and  young  woman 
must  be  quite  different  to  what  they  receive  at  the 
present  day  in  France.  On  the  one  hand,  the  young 
girl  must  be  prepared  to  fulfil  her  function  as  wife 
and  mother,  either  being  adapted  from  her  early 
years  to  the  social  environment  in  which  she  is  to 
be  developed,  or  being  made  strong  and  really 
virtuous,  instead  of  remaining  a  meek  dependant, 
always  exposed  to  the  risk  of  harm  if  the  super- 
vision of  which  she  is  the  object  becomes  relaxed. 
On  the  other  hand,  the  young  man  must  become 
accustomed  to  a  respect  for  the  rights  of  the  young 
woman,  and  this  will  be  all  the  easier  when  she  is 
able  to  claim  those  rights  with  more  moral  authority. 

If,  by  means  of  these  important  modifications  in 
the  relation  of  the  sexes  before  marriage,  love  may 
become  an  essential  factor  of  the  sexual  relations 
which  are  regularised  by  a  public  act,  woman  must 
not  after  her  marriage  lose  her  dignity  as  a  moral 
being.  She  is  man's  equal,  from  the  point  of  view  of 
law.  "The  idea  of  marriage  implies  this  equality, 
but  this  was  not  the  wish  of  the  man.  Injustice  has 
made  men  illogical ;  and  all  the  derogations  which 
the  need  of  safeguarding  personal  liberty,  and 
the  violation  of  duty  on  one  side  or  the  other, 
could  bring  into  the  law  of  monogamy,  have 
been  decided  exclusively  in  favour  of  the  man.  .  .  , 
Unfair  laws  and  even  more  unfair  customs  are  still 

1  Cf.  Comenius,  Didact,  45  ;  M  unroe,  The  Educational  Ideal,  pp. 
80  et  seq.;  Mabel  Hawtrey,  The  Co-education  of  the  Sexes  (Kegan 
Paul).— TR. 


DIVORCE    AND    DUTIES   TOWARDS    CHILDREN.    321 

in  contradiction  to  the  reason  which  created  mono- 
gamy, and  to  this  is  due  the  gap  between  the  real  and 
the  practical  social  ideal.  Hence  arose  the  establish- 
ment of  another  kind  of  slavery  formed  of  the  pariahs 
of  the  family.  Contempt  for  the  law  of  equality  in 
marriage  is  its  source."1 

Properly  speaking  then,  w7e  cannot  have  sub- 
ordination of  the  woman  to  the  man  without 
moral  decay.  The  harmony  realised  by  good  re- 
ciprocal dispositions,  by  the  mutual  understanding 
based  on  common  obedience  to  the  prescriptions  of 
reason,  can  alone  secure  the  stability  of  conjugal  life. 
When  in  a  family  there  is  a  master  and  subordinates, 
there  is  either  conflict  or  abdication,  a  state  of  war 
or  an  abnormal  weakening  of  will.  Marriage  and 
the  conjugal  life  should  therefore  be  founded  on 
reciprocal  esteem,  on  an  equal  respect  on  both  sides 
for  moral  dignity  and  individual  liberty,  on  an  affec- 
tionate sentiment  so  profound  and  lasting,  that  esteem 
and  respect  will  ever  form  part  of  those  sentiments 
which  can  only  be  experienced  at  the  price  of  re- 
newed and  more  and  more  painful  effort. 


157.  Divorce  and  Duties  towards  Children. 

The  right  of  divorce  is  the  consequence  of  this 
moral  precept ;  in  fact,  as  soon  as  love  or  affection, 
sincere  esteem,  and  goodwill  disappear  in  conjugal 
relationship,  why  should  we  be  compelled  to  lead  a 
common  life  which  becomes  more  and  more  unbear- 
able ?  In  the  days  of  barbarism,  when  woman  was 
considered  as  an  instrument  of  pleasure,  one  of  the 

1  Renouvier,  op.  cit.,  t.  i.  p.  579. 


322  THE    FAMILY,    FRIENDSHIP,    ETC. 

greatest  tasks  of  the  State,  in  those  days  intimately 
connected  with  the  Church,  was  to  prevent  the  in- 
cessantly reappearing  scandal  of  repudiation  for 
purely  sensual  reasons.  Divorce  was  then  pro- 
scribed, and  the  indissolubility  of  the  religious  and 
civil  bond  was  energetically  affirmed.  But  in  pro- 
portion as  we  advance  towards  a  social  state  based 
much  more  on  right  and  duty  than  on  force  and 
caprice,  divorce  becomes  an  indispensable  auxiliary 
of  family  morality — so  long  as  it  is  only  pronounced 
in  well-defined  cases,  and  with  all  the  guarantees  that 
can  be  offered  by  a  social  measure  regulated  by  well- 
defined  laws. 

If  there  are  children  of  the  marriage,  the  question 
of  divorce  becomes  from  the  moral  point  of  view 
still  more  complex,  as  it  is  no  longer  solely  a 
question  of  assuring  respect  for  the  individual  rights 
of  the  husband  and  wife,  but  of  securing  the  accom- 
plishment of  the  obligations  they  have  contracted 
with  respect  to  their  children.  From  the  sociological 
point  of  view,  the  principal  raison  d'etre  of  the  family 
is  the  duties  that  parents  owe  to  their  children.  The 
family,  like  the  city  and  the  State,  has  as  its  end  not 
so  much  the  exercise  of  a  power  as  the  accomplish- 
ment of  duties.  It  is  not  so  much  a  question  of  what 
the  pride  of  the  Roman  father,  the  patria  potestas,  did 
of  old,  as  of  the  numerous  obligations  that  nature 
and  reason  impose  on  parents  who  are  desirous  of 
playing  the  social  role  which  begins  with  the  very 
birth  of  their  children. 

The  solidarity  of  human  generations,  succeeding 
one  another  and  leaving  one  to  the  other  the  acquisi- 
tions of  past  centuries  added  to  those  of  the  present 
age,  makes  the  duty  of  the  present  generation  to  be 


DIVORCE    AND    DUTIES   TOWARDS    CHILDREN.    323 

an  incessant  preparation  for  the  social  future.  Society 
is  like  a  living  being,  which  tends  to  persevere  in  its 
being  and  to  develop  it.  It  endeavours  to  persist, 
and  therefore  it  assures  itself  of  the  future  by  the 
procreation  and  education  of  children.  The  first 
organ  of  social  survival  is  the  family.  It  may  be 
compared  for  two  reasons  to  the  organ  of  reproduc- 
tion :  first,  because  it  has  effectively  for  its  end  the 
birth  of  new  social  beings ;  and,  secondly,  because  by 
the  early  education  that  it  gives,  it  perpetuates  the 
collective  tradition,  and  transmits  to  new  genera- 
tions the  spirit,  the  manners,  the  language,  and  the 
aptitudes  of  previous  generations. 

If  we  can  no  longer  speak  of  the  rights  of  children, 
at  least  we  may  consider  the  rights  of  humanity  looked 
upon  as  a  kind  of  moral  personality,  as  a  system  in 
process  of  realisation,  whose  requirements  create 
duties  to  each  successive  generation,  duties  which 
become  greater  and  more  numerous  in  proportion 
as  we  advance  in  the  way  of  civilisation.  The 
family  responds  to  a  certain  number  of  these  re- 
quirements which  are  perceived  and  affirmed  by 
the  reason.  Hence  spring  the  duties  of  parents  to 
their  children,  quite  apart  from  the  fact  that  the 
natural  sympathy  of  strong  for  weak  beings,1  the 
sentiment  of  tenderness  to  the  children  that  one  has 
brought  into  the  world,2  must  determine  disposi- 
tions favourable  to  their  spontaneous  accomplish- 
ment. 

The  general  duty  of  procuring  for  the  child  all  its 
material  needs,  food,  clothes,  etc.,  is  not,  in  fact,  of 

1  Spencer  sees  in  this  sympathy  the  foundation  of  paternal  and 
maternal  love. 

2  Cf.  Bain  and  Espinas. 


324  THE    FAMILY,    FRIENDSHIP,    ETC. 

greater  importance  from  the  human  point  of  view, 
than  that  of  procuring  for  it  an  intellectual  and 
moral  environment  favourable  to  the  birth  of  those 
social  aptitudes  and  virtues  which  will  enable  it  to 
become  as  perfect  a  man  and  citizen  as  possible. 

There  is  therefore  a  grave  objection  to  the  dis- 
solution of  the  family,  either  by  the  hasty  dispersion 
of  its  members,  or  by  the  divorce  of  the  wedded  pair. 

There  are  many  cases  in  which  a  persistent  ex- 
ample of  scandalous  conduct  is  a  greater  obstacle  to 
the  proper  education  of  children  than  even  divorce 
itself.  There  are  other  cases  in  which,  in  spite  of  the 
profound  disagreement  of  parents,  a  common  solicitude 
for  their  children  obliges  the  husband  and  wife  not 
to  give  up  living  under  the  same  roof.  The  sense 
of  the  duties  contracted  with  respect  to  the  children 
should  survive  the  ruin  of  love,  affection,  and  esteem. 
Divorce,  the  deliberate  weakening  of  the  family 
spirit,  may  therefore  in  many  circumstances  assume 
a  character  of  immorality,  and  constitute  a  crime 
with  respect  to  society. 

158.  Duties  of  Children. 

We  may  speak  of  the  duties  of  children  towards 
their  parents,  since  the  former  seem  to  have  a  func- 
tion to  fulfil  with  respect  to  the  latter,  and  yet  there 
seems  to  be  no  reciprocity.  Classical  morality  teaches 
obedience  and  respect  as  the  principal  duties  of  the 
child.  Now,  no  beings  as  irreflective  as  children, 
with  a  moral  conscience  as  wavering  and  weak 
as  that  of  children,  can  understand  duty  and  really 
practise  moral  obligation.  They  have  only  the 
habits  and  rudiments  of  customs  that  suggestion 


DUTIES   OF   CHILDREN.  325 

or  education,  and  the  example  of  the  natural 
authority  of  strong  and  reasonable  beings  have  given 
them.  When  they  obey  it,  it  is  either  because  they 
have  not  the  least  doubt  as  to  the  importance  of  the 
command  they  have  received,  or  because  they  fear 
punishment.  The  authority  that  parents  have  over 
their  children  comes  to  them  rather  from  their  firm- 
ness, their  justice,  and  their  constancy,  than  from  the 
budding  morality  of  young  beings  in  whom  there 
scarcely  yet  exists  either  affection,  or  spontaneous 
sympathy,  or  gratitude  for  the  many  cares  and  many 
kindnesses  that  have  been  shown  them. 

And  when  it  is  a  question  of  young  people  who  are 
capable  of  reflection,  of  reasoning,  and  of  understand- 
ing a  moral  obligation,  the  obedience  that  is  due  is 
limited,  for  the  very  reason  that  a  moral  conscience 
is  entitled  to  a  certain  independence,  and  there  is  no 
true  morality  without  free  appreciation  and  an  ad- 
hesion exempt  from  restraint.  The  more  the  young 
man  exercises  his  reason,  the  more  he  is  independent 
from  the  moral  and  the  legal  point  of  view.  His 
parents  no  longer  represent  to  him  wider  experience. 
They  may  have  an  intellect  less  capable  than  his 
own,  a  less  powerful  mind,  and  a  less  reliable  practical 
judgment.  Often  they  represent  the  past,  that  is  to 
say,  the  conservative  and  timid  spirit,  the  enemy  of 
reform  and  of  bold  and  generous  enterprise. 

There  may  be  disobedience  on  the  part  of  the 
children,  or,  at  any  rate,  nonconformity  with  the 
advice  of  parents,  without  its  involving  any  lack  of 
respect.  Respect,  in  fact,  does  not  really  exist 
until  the  moral  being  is  in  the  presence  of  a  per- 
son having  a  high  moral  value.  One  may  differ  in 
opinion  with  a  person  whom  one  respects;  but  we 


326  THE    FAMILY,    FRIENDSHIP,    ETC. 

must  find  in  that  person  sincerity,  and  a  keen  desire 
to  possess  the  truth  and  to  do  his  duty. 

The  quite  young  child  has  no  real  respect ;  he 
has  either  fear,  if  he  has  been  accustomed  to  brutal 
treatment  and  threats,  or  a  kind  of  simple  admira- 
tion, such  as  Mr.  Baldwin1  has  pointed  out,  for  those 
superior  beings  who  seem  to  him  to  know  everything, 
to  be  able  to  give  him  the  final  explanation  of  every- 
thing, and  who  never  deceive  him  either  in  word  or 
act.  In  the  young  man  and  the  adult  there  is  more 
often  deference  than  real  esteem,  and  we  cannot 
say  that  respect  for  aged  parents  ought  to  be 
greater  than  that  which  is  due  to  honourable  and 
famous  old  men.  But  the  sentiment  which  is  not 
imposed,  and  which  morality  does  not  place  in  man's 
heart,  and  which  can  be  always  fortified  by  showing 
how  lawful  it  is,  and  how  well  it  agrees  with  the 
family  spirit  of  sociability,  is  filial  affection,  the  love 
for  those  beings  whose  devotion  and  self-denial  have 
often  been  the  admiration  of  persons  outside  the 
family  community. 

Thanks  to  this  strength  of  paternal  and  maternal, 
as  well  as  of  filial  love,  the  union  of  the  different  ele- 
ments will  not  remain  the  mere  effect  of  moral  will. 
The  spring  of  all  social  life  is  disinterested  sentiment, 
and  nowhere  is  it  more  necessary  than  here. 


159.  Friendship  and  Fraternity. 

The  tendency  to  sacrifice,  not  to  remain  closely 
circumscribed  by  the  first  community  with  which  the 
individual  comes  into  contact,  a  community  formed 

1  Moral  and  Social  Interpretation  of  Mental  Development,  1899. 


FRIENDSHIP    AND    FRATERNITY.  327 

at  its  birth,  which  sometimes  develops  what  might  be 
called  "  family  egoism,"  should  find  support  in  friend- 
ship. To  have  friends  is  a  duty;  the  man  who  has  no 
friends  is  not  in  general  a  moral  being.  In  antiquity, 
friendship  took  precedence  of  love.1  It  became  in  the 
days  of  Aristotle,  Epicurus,  and  the  Stoics,  a  kind  of 
social  virtue  from  which  even  the  selfishness  of  the 
Epicureans  did  not  venture  to  free  itself. 

Long  before,  and  in  all  primitive  societies,  the 
sentiments  of  devotion  to  a  friend,  of  sacrifice  for  a 
comrade  in  arms,  were  celebrated  as  noble  and 
worthy  of  heroes.  Friendship  only  flourishes  in 
the  midst  of  complete  social  activity,  hence  the 
Middle  Ages  were  fatal  to  this  sentiment.  The 
commercialism  of  the  present  day  is  equally  fatal 
to  it,  but  the  incontestable  development  of  tendencies 
to  solidarity  favours  it.  No  doubt  the  love  of  one's 
fellow-creatures  in  general,  and  the  union  of  our 
destiny  to  theirs  does  not  involve  that  freedom, 
confidence,  expansion  of  feeling,  and  community  of 
tendencies  which  make  friendship.  But  friendship 
is  at  any  rate  the  highest  degree  of  human  solidarity, 
and  everything  which  contributes  to  the  expansion 
of  our  generous  nature  is  in  favour  of  healthy  rela- 
tions between  men  who  have  daily  relations  with 
each  other. 

With  Aristotle,  and  in  spite  of  a  different  concep- 
tion of  the  value  and  of  the  role  of  woman,  we  do 
not  consider  love  and  friendship  as  incompatible. 
On  the  contrary,  the  love  which  is  not  allied  with 
friendship,  and  which  is  only  based  on  tendencies 

1  Cf.  Dugas,  L'Amitie  antiqttet  Paris,  Alcan.  Aristotle  thought  that 
woman  should  be  the  friend  of  man,  as  I  have  shown  in  my  course  of 
Lectures  at  the  College  des  Sciences  Sociales  in  1901. 


328  THE    FAMILY,    FRIENDSHIP,    ETC. 

which  are  very  easy  to  satisfy,  is  only  ephemeral. 
Friendship  thus  penetrates  the  family  life,  and  when 
it  is  a  question  of  children  in  the  same  household, 
it  takes  the  name  of  fraternity. 

In  fact,  from  the  sociological  and  psychological 
points  of  view,  there  is  no  difference  between  the 
sentiments  that  brothers  and  friends  experience  for 
each  other.  There  is  the  same  confidence,  devotion, 
and  community  of  interests.  For,  if  brothers  have 
common  family  interests,  friends  have  intellectual, 
sesthetical,  and  political  interests  in  common ;  and 
if  we  compare  the  power  of  both  from  the  point  of 
view  of  the  stability  of  the  ties  of  affection,  it  must 
be  admitted  that  the  latter  are  more  efficacious  than 
the  former,  and  that  the  former  must  be  reinforced 
by  the  latter  in  order  that  the  union  of  brothers  may 
remain  cordial  and  perfect. 


1 60.  Man  in  Relation  to  Animals. 

If  fraternity,  friendship,  and  family  relations  cannot 
make  us  forget  the  solidarity  of  all  human  beings,  and 
must  remain  inseparable  from  the  tendencies  to  the 
universal  good,  must  not  our  widest  humanitarian 
sentiments  be  reconciled  with  the  sympathy  which 
might  be  extended  to  the  whole  animal  kingdom  ? 

The  struggle  of  man  against  the  species  which 
endanger  his  existence  or  his  subsistence  is  lawful 
and  necessary;  but  the  torture  that  is  sometimes 
inflicted  on  brutes  and  wild  beasts  is  more  than 
unnecessary;  it  is  hateful,  for  it  betrays  low  senti- 
ments and  morbid  tendencies  to  cruelty  which  are 
unworthy  of  man.  It  is  sufficient  for  a  race  of 
reasonable  beings  to  guard  against  the  risks  that  their 


GENUINE    HUMAN    SENTIMENTS.  329 

work  may  run,  and  the  risks  that  they  themselves  may 
run,  from  the  representatives  of  the  lower  species, 
different  as  they  are  from  the  most  bloodthirsty 
and  the  most  ferocious  criminals,  because  of  their 
incapacity  to  amend  their  ways  and  to  approach  even 
ever  so  slightly  to  the  position  of  moral  personalities. 

A  fortiori  it  is  unworthy  of  man  to  ill-treat  the 
domestic  animals  which  do  him  service  and  are  his 
living  instruments.  Incidental  considerations  of  a 
metaphysical  order  should  bring  us  to  see  in  these 
inferior  brothers  beings  to  be  ever  improved  and 
raised  above  the  level  they  have  already  attained, 
and  therefore  to  be  taken  not  only  as  means  but 
also  as  ends.  In  this  way  the  rights  of  the  animal 
would  be  akin  to  those  of  the  child.  But  a  morality 
wrhich  has  a  psycho-sociological  foundation  would 
recognise  real  rights  in  beings  with  no  real  socia- 
bility; just  as  companies  of  animals  can  only  be 
called  "  societies  "  by  analogy,  so  the  title  of  animals 
to  our  sympathy  and  to  our  benevolence  can  only 
be  called  rights  by  a  distant  analogy  to  the  rights 
of  reasonable  beings. 

We  have  towards  animals  duties  which  are  a  part 
of  human  obligations  properly  so  called.  Animals 
have  no  rights  over  us,  but  we  have  rights  over  them 
on  account  of  those  duties  of  protection  and  bene- 
volence, etc.,  which  we  agree  to  fulfil,  and  especially 
because  of  the  higher  mission  which  man  has  under- 
taken to  organise  nature  as  a  whole. 

161.  Genuine  Human  Sentiments. 

For  the  better  fulfilment  of  this  mission,  humanity 
is  profoundly  distinguished  from  animality  by  the 


330  THE    FAMILY,    FRIENDSHIP,    ETC. 

development  of  the  characteristic  collective  senti- 
ments of  a  reasonable  being. 

In  fact,  nothing  is  of  more  importance  than  the 
systematisation  of  the  common  tendencies  by  which 
the  social  body  imposes  upon  the  individual  certain 
inclinations  and  certain  ways  of  thinking,  feeling, 
and  acting,  which,  in  default  of  individual  morality, 
none  the  less  cause  the  elevation  of  the  moral  level 
in  a  nation  or  a  race. 

For  the  individual  to  be  almost  without  difficulty 
or  effort  courageous,  clever,  wise,  and  temperate, 
his  environment  must  esteem  all  the  virtues  which  he 
wishes  to  acquire.  This  environment  must  be  for 
ever  holding  them  up  to  his  admiration,  and  must 
teach  him  nothing  but  aversion  from  vices  such  as 
brutality,  theft,  vengeance,  hypocrisy,  immodesty, 
intemperance,  selfishness,  etc. 

It  is  wrong  to  consider  such  qualities  as  frank- 
ness, veracity,  modesty,  boldness,  sobriety,  keen- 
ness for  work,  and  faults  such  as  dissimulation, 
effrontery,  debauchery,  and  idleness  as  private  virtues 
or  vices,  only  having  an  indirect  relation  to  social 
morality. 

In  general,  it  is  the  predominant  sentiments  in 
the  social  environment  that  cause  these  individual 
qualities  and  defects.  We  see  the  vices  that  I  have 
just  mentioned  rapidly  extended  in  certain  quarters, 
certain  cities,  or  certain  nations :  hypocrisy — be- 
cause the  popular  sentiment  being  in  favour  of 
formalism  imposes  a  feigned  generosity  on  avari- 
cious or  poor  people,  feigned  nobility  of  mind  on 
the  mean  spirited,  feigned  knowledge  on  the  ignor- 
ant ;  debauchery — because  luxury,  commercial  tend- 
encies, and  a  liking  for  inferior  appetites,  have 


GENUINE    HUMAN    SENTIMENTS.  331 

succeeded  in  obliterating  from  the  public  mind  the 
taste  for  beautiful  things,  for  science,  and  for  labour ; 
selfishness — either  because  the  spirit  of  economy  and 
of  mediocrity  has  become  general,  or  because  com- 
petition has  developed  in  a  more  or  less  extended 
circle  the  craving  for  material  interests  or  success. 
And  so  with  many  other  bad  habits  more  or  less 
harmful  to  collective  morality.  For  the  public 
virtues  to  be  gathered  into  a  single  group  like  in- 
dividual virtues,  for  them  to  be  closely  connected 
one  to  the  other,  and  for  the  development  of  the  one 
to  be  concomitant  with  that  of  the  rest,  we  must 
appeal  to  the  most  complex  collective  sentiment, 
and  it  can  only  fully  exist  in  the  common  conscious- 
ness when  all  the  others  exist  therein. 

Now,  true  charity  is .  the  love  of  one's  fellows 
with  a  view  to  their  continuous  perfection ;  true 
solidarity  is  that  of  beings  united  by  a  common 
nobility  of  sentiment.  To  be  charitable  in  the 
widest  sense  of  the  word  one  must  be  very  power- 
ful and  virtuous.  If  the  charitable  sentiment  is 
the  predominant  sentiment  of  a  whole  community, 
it  cannot  injure  individual  liberty,  equality,  or  rights 
of  any  kind.  Nothing  that  can  injure  the  perfection 
of  the  individual  and  that  of  the  community  can  be 
tolerated  in  that  sentiment. 

For  this  lofty  tendency  to  be  satisfied,  the  scien- 
tific, critical,  and  aesthetic  tendencies  which  lead 
to  the  possession  of  truth  and  artistic  enjoyment, 
and  which  also  have  as  their  consequence  veracity, 
frankness,  independence  of  mind,  and  disinterested- 
ness in  speculation  and  contemplation,  must  also 
as  a  preliminary  be  satisfied. 

When  a   city  is   proud   of  the   wisdom   and   the 


332  THE    FAMILY,    FRIENDSHIP,    ETC. 

talents  of  its  principal  citizens  it  is  already  not  very 
far  from  being  virtuous.  When  the  taste  for  in- 
struction, for  the  formation  of  the  mind  is  developed 
in  it,  superstition,  custom,  and  vile  appetites  are 
already  on  the  decrease.  Religious  sentiments  may 
sometimes  have  a  happy  influence ;  when  they  are 
pure,  or  inspired  by  metaphysical  belief  rather  than 
by  simple  faith  united  with  ignorance  and  super- 
stitious fear,  they  have  an  indisputable  aesthetic  and 
intellectual  value,  and  their  absence  cannot  but  be 
harmful  to  the  moral  elevation  of  a  city  and  of 
individuals. 

The  search  for  truth  and  the  love  of  the  beautiful 
can  only  be  accompanied  by  tendencies  to  healthy 
and  practical  belief  which  cannot  exist  without 
courage,  ardour,  worth,  firmness,  and  many  other 
virtues  which  make  man  upright  and  strong,  and 
the  community  powerful  and  honourable.  The 
spirit  of  chivalry  which  springs  from  a  vigilant 
opposition  to  everything  that  affects  one's  honour, 
and  to  everything  which  reveals  the  abuse  of  power, 
is  the  natural  consequence  of  loyalty,  courage,  and 
generosity  when  these  sentiments  are  held  in  honour 
in  the  community.  As  a  correlative  of  this  spirit 
in  man  we  have  in  woman  the  sentiment  of  modesty 
and  reserve,  which  is  contrasted  with  the  spirit  of 
luxury  or  ostentation,  and  the  gross  manners  in- 
spired by  low  inclinations.  Modesty  has  increased 
as  a  collective  sentiment  in  woman  in  proportion 
as  civilisation  has  freed  her  from  a  despotism  and 
from  a  very  often  degrading  yoke. 

The  more  independence  a  woman  has  the  more  she 
must  abstain  from  provoking  in  man  those  sensual 
feelings  which  are  founded  on  a  lack  of  respect  for 


GENUINE    HUMAN    SENTIMENTS.  333 

the  moral  person,  and  which  have  as  their  effect 
brutal  aggressions  or  insidious  tactics  which  are  more 
characteristic  of  the  lower  animals.  Moral  dignity 
is  imprinted  on  the  chastity  of  the  maid  and  the 
wife,  and  that  is  what  makes  it  so  valuable  to  the 
common  conscience.  When  the  public  spirit  allows 
without  protest  immodesty,  debauchery,  and  pros- 
titution, the  existence  of  the  worst  vices  may  be 
suspected. 

The  spirit  of  moderation,  tendencies  to  sobriety 
and  frugality,  on  condition  that  they  do  not  involve 
a  reprehensible  taste  for  mediocrity,  constitute  the 
very  basis  of  public  virtues.  A  people  prone  to 
excess  in  love  and  in  hatred  in  its  appetites  and  in 
its  inclinations,  lacks  stability,  and  places  an  insuper- 
able obstacle  in  the  way  of  all  moral  discipline. 

Thus,  from  the  sentiments  of  moderation  to  the 
spirit  of  charity  there  is  a  hierarchy  of  collective 
tendencies,  and  the  regular  development  and  sub- 
ordination of  these  tendencies  to  a  sublime  sentiment 
of  fraternity  can  alone  assure  social  and  individual 
morality. 


PART  IV. 

THE  STRUGGLE  AGAINST  IMMORALITY. 

I.  SOCIAL  RESPONSIBILITY. 

1 62.  Conditions  of  Responsibility.  Intention  —  1 63. 
Errors  of  Appreciation — 164.  Insufficient  Deliberation 
— 165.  Irresponsibility — 166.  Possible  Modification  of 
the  Character — 167.  Imput ability — 168.  Social  Action. 

II.  SANCTION  AND  MORAL  EDUCATION. 

169.  Role  and  Nature  of  Sanction — 170.  Happiness  the 
Natural  Consequence  of  Moral  Action—  171.  Merit — 172. 
The  Immorality  of  Punishment — 173.  Utilitarian  Role  of 
Punishment —  1 74.  Moral  Suggestion. 


I. 

SOCIAL  RESPONSIBILITY. 

162.  Conditions  of  Responsibility.     Intention. 

WE  have  now  seen  how  individual  and  collective 
morality  are  each  in  turn  subordinated  to  a  system 
of  tendencies,  any  defect  in  which  involves  crime, 
misdemeanour,  or  fault.  For  good  actions  to  be 
accomplished,  the  individual,  the  State,  the  family, 
the  association,  the  city,  should  be  submitted  in 
their  evolution  to  certain  rules  which  flow  from  a 
scientific  conception  of  the  social  ideal  as  a  whole ; 

334 


CONDITIONS    OF    RESPONSIBILITY.  335 

each  element  or  group  must  have  its  own  tendency, 
but  that  tendency  must  be  harmonised  with  the 
tendency  of  the  whole. 

If  it  be  not  so,  and  if  we  may  not  hope  that  it  \\  ill 
ever  be  so, — for  no  doubt  there  always  will  be  in  a 
system  as  complex  as  humanity  disorders,  abnormal 
facts,  and  reprehensible  acts, — who  are  the  guilty  ? 
and  how  are  the  guilty  to  be  punished  ?  or  rather, 
if  there  are  no  guilty  whom  one  ought  to  punish, 
on  whom  should  fall  the  responsibility  for  misde- 
meanours, and  what  ought  to  be  done  to  prevent 
repetition  of  the  faults  ? 

Let  us  first  examine  under  what  conditions 
responsibility  is  established.  Moralists  from  the 
days  of  Kant  have  as  a  rule  connected  responsi- 
bility with  intention.  Let  us  then  analyse  this  new 
fact. 

Kant  endeavoured  to  reduce  intention  to  moral 
respect,  and  this  respect  to  a  sentiment  of  dis- 
interestedness and  humility  in  our  ego,  and  of 
admiration  for  the  moral  law.1 

Besides,  Kant  perceived  little  in  the  throng  of 
motives  antagonistic  to  morality  but  egoism  and 
presumption  (self-love  and  self-satisfaction).  In 
that  case,  the  moral  idea  can  only  consist  of  an 
antagonistic  sentiment  which  is  also  but  slightly 
complex.2 

Moral  intention  in  the  psychological  processus 
must  be  replaced  by  voluntary  deliberation,  so  that 
we  may  see  simultaneously  its  variability  and  its 
importance.  The  vague  sentiment  of  doing  one's 

1  Cf.    "The  springs  of  pure  practical  reason,"  Kritik  of  Practical 
Reason. 
3  Jbid.t  p.  130. 


336  SOCIAL    RESPONSIBILITY. 

duty  cannot  satisfy  us.  We  desire  to  fulfil  a  deter- 
mined obligation,  and  as  far  as  possible  to  fulfil 
all  the  obligations  the  totality  of  which  gives  us 
a  function  in  the  social  system.  Now  can  we  simul- 
taneously perceive  all  our  obligations  ?  can  we 
under  given  circumstances  think  of  the  manifold 
duties  which  are  incumbent  upon  us  ?  Is  not  the 
time  for  the,  deliberation  which  is  at  our  disposal 
for  evoking  our  different  obligations  almost  always 
too  short  considering  the  weakness  of  our  intellect  ; 
and  are  we  not  in  a  large  number  of  cases  conscious 
of  our  limited  aptitude  to  examine  every  side  of  a 
question,  and  to  judge  of  all  the  consequences  which 
immediately  result  from  our  acts  ?  (I  do  not  speak 
of  remote  consequences,  most  of  which  escape  us.) 
And  does  there  not  follow  from  this  intellectual 
incapacity  a  sentiment,  almost  of  melancholy,  which 
makes  us  decide  to  act  while  we  are  fully  conscious 
of  running  a  risk,  the  risk  of  self-deception  ?  But 
another  sentiment  immediately  springs  into  being 
by  contrast,  that  of  having  done  as  much  as  possible 
to  diminish  the  importance  of  the  risk  that  is  run. 

Those  who  are  not  conscious  of  their  relative 
intellectual  weakness,  of  their  incapacity  to  perceive 
all  the  consequences  of  their  decision,  do  not  ex- 
perience this  feeling  of  risk.  They  have  no  anxiety 
beyond  the  sphere  of  the  effects  foreseen. 

For  these  effects  to  be  accepted,  and  for  their  cause 
to  be  admitted  with  moral  intention  as  the  end  of 
the  voluntary  act,  they  must  satisfy  certain  tendencies. 
Now  it  very  rarely  happens  that  this  is  a  simple 
desire  for  systematic  action,  purely  moral,  and  con- 
stituting the  whole  intention.  It  may  happen  that 
certain  tendencies,  some  generous,  others  selfish, 


ERRORS  or  APPRECIATION.  337 

some  aesthetic,  and  others  quite  inferior,  may  all  share 
in  the  voluntary  determination  and  combine  their 
influence.  Frequently  one  desire  appears  as  pre- 
dominant and  masks  the  importance  of  others, 
less  lofty  or  quite  different,  which  also  urge  to 
action,  and  are  inseparable  from  moral  intention  pro- 
perly so  called.  And  further,  the  desire  for  rational 
ends,  for  action  morally  good,  may  appear  in  us  after 
selfish  desires  or  appetites  of  an  inferior  order 
have  already  determined  our  choice,  and  when  the 
moral  intention  is  only  a  cloak  under  which  are  dis- 
guised quite  different  intentions,  of  which  our  con- 
science is  the  dupe. 

What  is  then  in  this  case  the  value  of  intention 
from  the  point  of  view  of  the  responsibility  of  the 
agent  ?  Shall  we  say  that  because  the  intention  was 
good,  because  the  agent  sincerely  believed  that  he 
was  doing  his  duty,  he  is  not  responsible  for  the 
fatal  consequences  of  his  choice  ?  Is  it  not  far  better 
to  see  the  real  motives  of  the  voluntary  decision,  and 
ought  we  not  to  consider  the  efficient  factors  rather 
than  the  apparent  factor  ? 

163.  Errors  of  Appreciation. 

How  many  people  are  deceived  as  to  the  moral 
value  of  the  ends  which  they  propose  to  themselves, 
and  of  the  desires  which  urge  them  to  propose  to 
themselves  such  ends. 

The  old  Socratic  doctrine  which  declared  that  no 
one  was  voluntarily  wicked,  borrows  some  force  from 
this  consideration.  Few  men  are  conscious  of  the 
baseness  of  their  motives,  and  almost  all  are  under 
an  illusion  as  to  the  real  motives  of  their  voluntary 

22 


SOCIAL   RESPONSIBILITY. 

decisions.  How  can  a  being,  born  amid  prostitution, 
brought  up  in  the  low  quarters  of  a  great  town,— 
how  can  he,  in  his  physical  and  moral  degeneration, 
conceive  as  immoral  the  highest  tendencies  that  he 
has  ever  known  within  him,  tendencies  which,  in 
reality  and  for  a  man  in  other  circumstances,  would 
be  gross  appetites  ?  Would  he  not  abandon  himself 
to  these  inferior  tendencies,  which,  to  be  curbed, 
require  the  most  elevated  inclinations  and  com- 
plete self-control,  because  he  ignores  inclinations 
which  have  proved  to  be  the  moral  safeguard  of 
others  ? 

It  may  be  objected  that  he  knows  perfectly  well 
that  he  is  doing  wrong.  The  proof  of  it  is  in  his 
dissimulation.  He  hides  himself  in  order  that  he 
may  gratify  his  grosser  appetites.  We  are  too  often 
deceived  in  this  matter.  The  being  that  is  inferior 
from  the  moral  point  of  view  sometimes  flees  from 
social  reprobation,  sometimes  fears  the  police,  and 
knows  that  he  is  acting  contrary  to  the  prescriptions 
of  law  and  morals ;  but  either  he  cannot  resist  his 
all-powerful  appetites — he  is  obsessed  by  them,  and 
must  give  way  to  more  and  more  violent  impulses — 
or  he  hates  the  society  that  he  fears,  he  mocks  at 
morals  that  he  cannot  understand,  and  he  breaks 
the  law  in  which  he  sees  only  a  formula  of  oppres- 
sion, and  not  an  expression  of  moral  obligation.1 

In  the  first  case  he  must  be  satisfied  by  the 
struggle,  although  it  cannot  issue  in  an  effective 

1  This    is    the    case  with    a   young   man  named   N ,   who  was 

condemned  at  the  Assizes  of  Orne  for  indecent  assault,  and  who 
was  declared  responsible  for  his  acts  because  he  hid  himself  in  order  to 
give  way  to  his  instincts  as  an  inferior  being.  He  was  unanimously 
considered  to  be  "  unintelligent." 


ERRORS   OF   APPRECIATION.  339 

abstention  from  wrong.  This  delinquent  or  criminal 
is  not  voluntarily  wicked,  but  is  so  against  his  will. 
In  the  second  case  he  hides  himself,  and  flees  before 
a  force  superior  to  his  own  ;  but  he  does  not  see  in 
that  force  anything  moral ;  he  does  not  see  in  his 
own  ends  anything  wrong  or  immoral.  If  he  does 
not  know  what  is  forbidden,  he  does  not  understand 
why  it  is  forbidden.  He  does  not  therefore  do 
wrong  in  order  to  do  wrong ;  he  does  it  because 
what  we  call  wrong  is  nevertheless  to  him  the  best 
thing  that  he  can  think  of. 

The  man  with  really  evil  intentions,  the  criminal 
who  refrains  from  doing  good  because  it  is  good,  who 
struggles  against  social  institutions  because  they  are 
the  creations  of  public  morality,  who  slays,  robs,  and 
slanders  in  order  to  assert  the  wickedness  of  which 
he  is  conscious,  and  which  he  knowingly  fosters 
within  him, — has  such  a  being  as  this,  a  being 
abnormal  in  the  highest  degree,  ever  existed  ?  If, 
therefore,  we  ought  only  to  be  responsible  for  crime 
when  it  has  been  committed  with  evil  intention,  we 
never  would  be  responsible.  Moralists  who  have 
made  of  intention  the  foundation  of  responsibility 
have  therefore  considered  as  contrary  to  good  inten- 
tion any  passion,  tendency,  desire,  or  appetite, 
other  than  disinterestedness  and  respect  for  the 
law  of  duty. 

But  how  many  acts  useful  to  society,  useful  to  the 
development  of  a  moral,  social,  or  individual  system, 
are  due  to  tendencies  or  even  to  appetites  which  have 
not  been  accompanied  by  any  sentiment  of  respect 
or  disinterestedness  ?  Must  they  therefore  be  con- 
demned ?  and  if  it  is  absurd  to  consider  them  as 
immoral,  where  will  immorality  in  intention  begin  ? 


34°  SOCIAL    RESPONSIBILITY. 

There  will  probably  be  only  amorality.  There  will 
only  be  two  categories  of  beings — moral  beings  and 
amoral  beings. 

164.  Insufficient  Deliberation. 

If,  when  we  wish  to  attain  an  end  and  make 
our  arrangements  to  that  effect,  we  realise  an  end 
that  could  not  be  foreseen,  this  is  called  accident 
(the  identical  definition  given  by  Aristotle),  chance, 
fatality.  In  it  there  is  no  merit,  nor  is  there  crime, 
misdemeanour,  or  fault.  And  this  is  much  more  the 
case  when  the  consequences  might  have  been  fore- 
seen, although  they  were  not.  The  sportsman  who 
fires  into  a  public  thicket  where  he  must  have  known 
there  may  be  other  sportsmen,  commits  an  act  of 
serious  imprudence.  His  deliberation  has  been  in- 
sufficient. He  has  not  summed  up  certain  motives 
for  not  firing  into  the  thicket,  and  he  ought  to  have 
done  so  for  his  act  to  be  marked  as  the  result  of  the 
exercise  of  reasonable  will. 

If  he  has  done  so,  and  yet  the  desire  of  firing 
was  the  stronger  ;  if  the  fear  of  an  accident  vanished 
from  his  mind  or  barely  arose,  his  responsibility  is 
even  greater  than  before.  He  ought  to  have  fortified 
in  his  mind  the  motive  of  abstaining,  strengthened 
it  by  fresh  motives,  and  fixed  his  attention  on  this 
important  point. 

But  if  in  the  first  case  the  fear  of  accident  has  not 
arisen,  and  if  in  the  second  case  it  has  not  persisted, 
the  psychologist  ought  to  discover  why.  Perhaps 
the  sportsman  was  not  intelligent  enough  to  em- 
bark upon  such  subtle  considerations.  Perhaps 
he  lacked  generous  sentiments,  or  was  urged  not 


INSUFFICIENT    DELIBERATION.  341 

to  prolong  his  reflection  and  deliberation  by  his 
selfishness,  or  by  his  levity,  or  by  the  simple  at- 
traction of  pleasure.  If  he  lacked  intelligence  or 
feelings,  if  the  impulse  to  seek  a  pleasure  destroyed 
in  him  all  power  of  reflection,  and  inhibited  every 
antagonistic  tendency,  and  if,  although  it  was  morally 
his  duty  to  deliberate  in  a  certain  manner,  and 
psychologically  he  was  unable  to  do  so  because  of 
his  mental  debility,  what  becomes  of  his  responsi- 
bility ?  Is  it  greater  than  that  of  the  dog  which, 
while  playing  with  a  little  child,  upsets  it  on  the 
ground  and  seriously  injures  it  ? 

In  most  cases,  when  the  course  of  deliberation  is 
too  hastily  interrupted,  it  is  at  a  given  moment,  and 
either  the  circumstances  require  an  immediate  solu- 
tion, or  perhaps  we  have  reached  one  of  those  states 
of  consciousness  which  can  persist  during  a  certain 
time,  and  which  are  marked  as  halting-places  in  the 
course  of  the  mental  processus.  Why  at  this  moment 
does  action  begin  to  succeed  to  speculation,  instead 
of  allowing  the  latter  to  continue  ?  Is  it  due  to  a 
kind  of  intellectual  lassitude  ?  In  certain  cases  it 
might,  in  fact,  be  too  fatiguing  for  the  mind  to 
continue  to  deliberate  and  to  discuss  the  pros  and 
cons. 

In  most  cases  there  is  probably  an  impatience  to 
issue  from  a  painful  state  of  indecision.  Here  it  is 
that  the  character  plays  a  considerable  part ;  accord- 
ing as  one  is  quick  or  slow,  ardent  or  temperate,  the 
painful  sentiment  which  accompanies  every  de- 
liberation leads  more  or  less  quickly  to  a  solution 
which  is  very  often  hasty  in  the  first  case,  and 
sometimes  too  slow  to  arrive  in  the  second. 

How   can    a   man    be   considered   responsible    for 


342  SOCIAL    RESPONSIBILITY. 

the  temperament  and  the  character  which  thus 
determine  his  hasty  choice  ? 

No  doubt  a  means  of  making  ourselves  responsible 
for  a  check  midway  can  be  imagined.  It  is  said  that, 
if  we  are  free,  our  liberty  consists  in  not  allowing 
our  choice  to  be  fixed  until  after  a  certain  interval 
of  deliberation ;  thus,  Malebranche  believed  that 
owing  to  liberty,  "the  impulse  that  we  have  to- 
wards the  universal  good  is  not  entirely  checked 
by  a  particular  good.  The  mind  is  urged  to  go 
further.  .  .  .  Liberty  consists  in  being  able  to  sus- 
pend its  judgment  and  its  love,  and  later  think  of 
other  things,  and  therefore  love  other  forms  of 
good."1 

But  Malebranche  conceived  a  limit  to  this  pro- 
gress of  the  mind  in  the  consideration  of  good.  It 
was  a  question  of  reaching  by  liberty  "that  which 
contains  all  good";  so  that  liberty  and  love  of  good 
being  synonymous,  a  strong  tendency  to  satisfy  God, 
was  the  exact  equivalent  of  liberty  in  the  system  of 
Malebranche. 

This  tendency  might  be  more  or  less  powerful, 
and  according  to  its  power  in  each  being,  Male- 
branche conceived  those  beings  as  more  or  less  free. 
In  the  same  way  we  have  recognised  in  every  man 
a  strong  tendency  to  systematic  action,  to  conduct 
that  is  quite  coherent  in  itself  and  well  co-ordinated 
with  that  of  all  its  fellows  in  view  of  a  common  end. 
According  to  the  power  that  this  tendency  has  in 
him,  the  moral  agent  pursues  his  deliberations,  more 
or  less  at  length,  with  the  object  of  only  adopting  a 
decision  that  is  in  conformity  with  his  reason.  Is 
that  liberty  ?  and  can  one  be  said  to  be  responsible 

1  Recherche  de  la  Verite,  Vol.  i.,  Bk.  i.,  Chap.  i. 


IRRESPONSIBILITY.  343 

because  one  has  weaker  or  stronger  tendencies, 
because  one  has  a  more  or  less  marked  taste  for 
systematic  activity  qua  an  individual  and  moral 
being  ? l  We  must,  in  particular,  remark  that  here  is 
an  essential  tendency,  one  of  those  that  some  of  the 
habits  instilled  by  education  or  acquired  by  pro- 
longed effort  cannot  succeed  in  establishing  within  us. 

We  are  born  more  or  less  reasonable,  more  or  less 
adapted  to  moral  activity,  just  as  we  are  born  more 
or  less  able  to  represent  to  ourselves  colours  or 
sounds. 

And  so  it  is  with  all  those  lofty  tendencies  which 
we  have  recognised  as  indispensable  to  morality,  the 
sum-total  of  which,  as  \ve  have  seen,  forms  the  moral 
character.  Are  we  responsible  for  the  absence  within 
us  of  a  generous  tendency  which  would  serve  as  an 
antagonistic  reducer  to  a  low  passion  ?  But  then  the 
question  presents  itself  as  to  how  far  we  share  in  the 
recognised  irresponsibility  of  the  insane. 


165.  Irresponsibility. 

This  is  one  of  the  most  important  questions  in 
morality.  For  if  vice  is  a  natural  product  like  sugar 

1  Besides,  experience  shows  that  prolonged  deliberation  is  sometimes 
injurious  to  rational  action.  There  are  people  who  cannot  make  up 
their  minds  to  take  a  side,  who  are  ever  summoning  up  new  ends  and 
feelings  in  contrary  directions,  so  that  the  conception  of  the  act  is 
modified  while  the  clearly  conscious  desires  become  enfeebled,  while 
appetites  are  obscured,  and  while  tendencies  assume  greater  and 
greater  authority.  Thus  we  reach  the  state  in  which  we  no  longer 
decide  for  clear  and  assignable  reasons,  for  reasons  Capable  of  being 
formulated  into  judgments  and  reasonings  of  objective  value,  but  simply 
by  sentiments,  by  a  kind  of  impulse  rising  like  a  huge  wave  from  the 
depths  of  the  unconscious. 


344  SOCIAL    RESPONSIBILITY. 

and  vitriol,  if  it  no  longer  depends  on  men  to  re- 
main virtuous  and  to  become  vicious  any  more  than 
it  depends  on  them  to  remain  healthy-minded  or  to 
become  insane ;  a  fortiori,  if  certain  unfortunate 
creatures  are  born  criminals  just  as  others  are  born 
mad,  or  of  incurable  mental  weakness;  if  misde- 
meanour is  always  or  almost  always  inevitable,  what 
is  the  use  of  morality  ?  what  is  the  good  of  a  theory 
which  proposes  to  us  an  ideal  and  rules  of  systematic 
conduct,  which  we  necessarily  misunderstand,  and 
the  more  inevitably  as  we  are  nearer  in  the  psychic 
hierarchy  to  that  inferior  degree  which  corresponds 
to  the  maximum  of  moral  insanity  ?  The  intimate 
relation  between  crime  and  degeneration  is,  how- 
ever, more  and  more  probable.  If  we  distinguish,  in 
scientific  environments,  between  morbid  and  ordinary 
crime,  it  is  no  doubt  because  of  the  medico-legal  pre- 
occupations of  most  alienists  who  are  compelled,  in 
the  presence  of  a  criminal,  to  give  an  opinion  as  to 
his  irresponsibility,  and  in  general  as  to  his  confine- 
ment in  a  lunatic  asylum,  or  as  to  his  responsibility 
with  the  legal  consequences  that  it  involves.  They 
must  therefore  arbitrarily  establish  a  certain  degree 
of  intellectual  and  affective  trouble  above  which  the 
delinquents  are  declared  responsible,  and  the  princi- 
pal difficulty  of  their  task  lies  exactly  in  that  arbitrary 
determination.  The  motives  for  impulsive  crime  are 
grasped  easily  enough,  and  from  the  moment  they 
are  grasped  we  excuse  the  wrongdoing  to  that 
extent ;  but  we  no  longer  can  grasp  the  motives  of  a 
crime  that  is  committed  in  cold  blood.  There  we 
see  the  intervention  of  will,  and  admit  a  much  greater 
culpability ;  but  the  voluntary  crime  and  the  im- 
pulsive crime  are  alike  determined  by  a  motive.  The 


IRRESPONSIBILITY.  >.|5 

surprising  thing  is  that  the  act  in  the  first  corresponds 
to  so  slight  an  interest,  whereas  in  the  second, 
impulse  has  given  so  great  an  interest  to  the  wrong 
that  has  been  done.  One  is  surprised  to  see  that  to 
procure  a  transient  pleasure  for  the  petty  satisfaction 
of  self-love,  or  even  for  less  still,  a  prolonged  delibera- 
tion may  have  issued  in  lavish  precaution  and  skill  in 
the  execution  of  a  cleverly  conceived  design. 

And  is  not  this  precisely  the  sign  of  the  pathologi- 
cal character  of  such  an  action  and  such  a  mental 
processus  ?  We  are  presented  with  a  kind  of 
dilemma :  either  the  interest  was  considerable,  and 
in  that  case  the  crime  is  similar  to  impulsive  crime — 
the  crime  and  the  criminal  are  alike  pathological ;  or 
there  is  practically  no  interest,  and  then  the  action 
becomes  inexplicable  by  the  determining  causes 
of  normal  action,  and  the  crime  is  pathological. 
For  how  can  we  admit  that  except  from  mental 
aberration  a  reasonable  being  prefers  an  act  which, 
if  it  were  normal,  would  be  opposed  by  his  social 
tendencies  and  the  sentiments  that  are  innate  in  him 
and  developed  by  education  ?  He  cannot  therefore 
experience  those  sentiments  which  in  healthy-minded 
men  serve  as  a  counterpoise  to  tendencies  to  offensive 
action. 

Or  will  it  again  be  objected  that  the  influence  of 
the  will  is  capable  of  keeping  the  attention  freely  on 
the  motive  which,  it  would  have  seemed,  ought  to 
have  been  the  weaker,  and  which  thus  becomes  the 
more  powerful  ?  The  hypothesis  of  a  free  will 
capable  of  arbitrarily  modifying  the  natural  play 
which  constitutes  deliberation  is,  as  I  have  said,  a 
metaphysical  hypothesis  which,  like  all  similar  hypo- 
theses, has  the  grave  inconvenience  of  introducing  an 


34-6  SOCIAL    RESPONSIBILITY. 

entity,  the  will,  which  we  can  only  indicate  without 
exact  definition.  Science  ought  to  be  content  with 
facts  and  laws,  and  the  factors  of  will  are,  as  we  have 
seen,  choices  determined  by  the  nature  of  the  char- 
acter and  by  the  tendencies  essential  to  the  individual. 
If,  therefore,  a  motive  that  is  very  feeble  in  upright 
and  honourable  people  is  suddenly  found  in  an  in- 
dividual to  have  the  support  of  his  whole  ego,  so  far 
as  to  reduce  to  nil  the  effect  of  all  other  motives,  and 
to  orientate  in  a  criminal  direction  the  processus  of 
deliberation  which  issues  in  his  so-called  free  choice, 
is  not  the  character  of  that  individual  exceptional  and 
abnormal  in  the  highest  degree  ?  Is  not  this  indi- 
vidual a  being  of  a  fundamentally  pathological  nature  ? 
We  thus  come  back  to  what  we  said  before,  namely, 
that  he  lacks  tendencies  that  are  indispensable  to  the 
normal  being,  and  that  among  those  essential  tend- 
encies are  not  to  be  found  those  which  he  ought  to 
experience  in  order  to  have  a  normal  nature. 

1 66.  Possible  Modification  of  the  Character. 

Can  it  have  tendencies,  and,  having  them,  can 
they  be  preserved  ?  Not  having  them,  can  it  desire 
to  acquire  them  ?  These  questions  require  further 
examination  as  to  the  wray  in  which  the  man  may 
lose  or  acquire  essential  tendencies,  tendencies 
dominating  his  mental  evolution,  or  in  all  cases 
strong  enough  to  direct  his  conduct.  Can  it  happen 
by  his  own  effort  alone,  and  in  virtue  of  his  own 
choice  ?  Yes,  undoubtedly  it  can,  on  condition  that 
it  is  by  the  development  or  natural  transformation  of 
pre-existing  tendencies  and  fundamental  appetites. 
But  if  these  elements  or  rudiments  do  not  pre-exist, 


POSSIBLE    MODIFICATION    OF   THE    CHARACTER.    347 

neither  natural  effort  nor  even  education  can  bring 
them  into  being,  and  the  individual  we  are  consider- 
ing must  then  be  classed  among  the  morally  insane 
whose  moral  debility  is  congenital. 

On  the  other  hand,  moral  tendencies  are  so  com- 
plex that  at  first  they  may  be  affected  by  a  slow 
dissolution  of  the  personality,  and  nothing  can 
prevent  their  natural  decay  or  their  ultimate  dis- 
appearance. Here  then  is  a  being,  apparently 
provided  with  free-will,  but  to  whom  deliberation 
and  will  are  no  longer  of  any  use  from  the  moral 
point  of  view,  and  on  whom  only  quite  simple 
impulses  make  any  impression.  You  call  him  a 
responsible  criminal.  He  is  already,  although  it  is 
not  apparent,  nearly  related  to  the  "  morally  insane." 

The  impulsive  man  may  be  of  a  less  morbid  nature. 
Passion,  in  fact,  is  inhibitive  to  tendencies  that  it 
cannot  subordinate  to  itself.  It  does  not  destroy 
them,  and  when  it  has  passed  away  it  may  leave 
dominant  the  very  tendencies  that  it  had  over- 
shadowed. Its  development,  up  to  the  paroxysm 
that  is  sometimes  so  fatal,  can  only  be  due  to  an 
excessive  compliance  in  the  subject  with  certain  of 
these  inclinations  or  certain  of  his  appetites  to  an 
indolence  which  certain  situations  and  certain  circum- 
stances encourage.  The  impulsive  criminal  would  be 
able  in  most  cases  to  escape  from  the  thraldom  of 
passion  by  an  energetic  intervention  of  his  will,  that 
is  to  say,  by  an  appeal  to  all  the  tendencies  of  his 
character — tendencies  which  may  be  normal,  and 
which  in  their  totality  are  the  constituents  of  a 
normal  nature.  If  he  had  been  accustomed  to  self- 
control  he  might  have  avoided  his  crime.  He  is 
therefore  more  guilty  than  the  man  who  finds  within 


348  SOCIAL    RESPONSIBILITY. 

himself  in  the  depths  of  his  being,  however  pro- 
longed his  deliberation  may  be,  no  tendencies 
capable  of  opposing  an  abnormal  desire. 

It  is  right  to  say  that  voluntary  crimes  reveal  a 
fundamentally  vicious  temperament,  while  impulsive 
crimes  are  generally  committed  by  occasional  mis- 
demeanants. But  for  that  very  reason  degenerates 
of  every  kind,  attacked  by  a  more  or  less  characteristic 
moral  insanity,  must  be  brought  into  close  relation 
with  the  authors  of  voluntary  crimes.  As  for  the 
impulsive,  they  are  also  morbid,  for  the  impulse 
which  leads  to  crime  can  only  be  developed  and 
become  omnipotent  in  a  being  in  whom  mental 
instability,  and,  in  particular,  the  instability  of 
tendencies,  is  already  great  enough  to  constitute  a 
serious  blemish.  Therefore  criminals,  to  whatever 
class  they  may  belong,  must  be  considered  as 
diseased  ;  they  either  have  lacked  stability  in  the 
tendencies  that  are  characteristic  of  a  responsible 
man,  or  they  have  suffered  a  check  in  their  develop- 
ment, or  a  reversion  which  has  deprived  them  of 
some  of  those  tendencies,  while  it  weakens  their 
power  and  causes  them  to  disappear,  and  to  make 
way  for  others  which  have  very  soon  become  morbid.1 

167.  Immutability. 

But,  many  moralists  will  object,  if  we  go  back 
in  this  way  from  responsibility  to  responsibility, 

1  In  fact,  it  is  ascertained  that  criminals  in  general  present  a  morbid 
exaggeration  of  tendencies  either  of  nutrition,  or  reproduction,  or  the 
preservation  of  the  personal  existence,  or  of  some  of  the  tendencies 
derived  from  these.  That  is  why  M.  Lacassagne  divided  criminals 
into  three  categories — frontal,  parietal,  and  occipital— according  to  the 
supposed  localisation  of  the  different  tendencies. 


IMPUTABILITY.  349 

imputability  ends  by  being  lost  in  the  waves  of  an 
indefinitely  remote  past,  and  of  a  totality  of  circum- 
stances indefinitely  remote.  We  must  therefore 
distinguish  between  moral  responsibility  and  im- 
putability. We  have  already  seen  that  if  the  partisans 
of  liberty  reap  nothing  from  ignorance  as  far  as  the 
point  of  departure  of  our  character  is  concerned, 
neither  can  it  profit  those  who  prefer  to  argue  from 
fatality  or  universal  determinism  in  order  to  excuse 
their  errors. 

The  legislator  and  the  moral  agent  have  both  the 
right  and  the  duty  of  considering  the  positive  datum 
of  a  primitive  characteristic  which  is  irreducible,  and 
which  is  the  origin  of  the  acts  accomplished  by  the 
personality.  It  is  to  this  character,  which  is  at  once 
the  starting-point  and  the  point  of  departure  (the 
effect  of  manifold  influences  of  sociological,  psycho- 
logical, biological,  physico-chemical,  and  mechanical 
influences,  but  the  immediate  cause  of  new  series  of 
phenomena  which  could  not  have  appeared  without 
the  constitution  of  a  fresh  personality),  that  we 
must  at  first  look  for  the  reason  of  a  crime  or  mis- 
demeanour. If  it  were  committed  through  weakness 
of  tendencies  or  character,  we  might  ask  the  agent 
to  strengthen  what  is  best  in  him,  what  ought  to 
become  predominant;  and  if  he  does  not  do  so, 
although  he  has  the  power,  he  is  responsible  for  the 
crimes  which  his  weakness  involves.  If  the  crime 
were  committed  through  fundamental  wickedness 
and  through  baseness  of  that  character  which  is  a 
product  of  factors,  does  that  mean  that  he  has  no 
responsibility?  No  doubt,  the  individual  has  none; 
but  because  a  morally  insane  person  can  no  longer 
resist  his  impulses  or  cannot  actually  give  to  his 


350  SOCIAL    RESPONSIBILITY. 

accurate  reasonings  the  practical  consequences  which 
they  imply,  does  it  follow  that  society  could  not,  by 
commencing  at  a  sufficiently  early  stage  a  specialised 
education,  give  this  patient  the  means  of  avoiding 
crime,  develop  in  him  healthier  sentiments,  and  give 
to  his  sensibility  and  to  his  practical  judgment  an 
impulse  of  another  kind  ? 

1 68.  Social  Action. 

It  is  objected,  that  from  their  earliest  years  many 
of  the  morally  insane  have  been  incurably  unrespon- 
sive to  educative  action.  But  is  not  this  because 
the  education  they  have  received  has  not  been  in 
the  least  suitable  to  their  temperament  and  their 
character  ?  And  is  it  not  also  because  the  education 
received  by  criminals  who  are  not  considered  insane 
has  been  insufficient,  incomplete,  ill  directed,  and  too 
early  abandoned,  that  they  have  committed  a  crime 
which  perhaps  their  temperament,  left  to  its  free 
development,  has  rendered  inevitable  ? * 

What  the  individual  is  powerless  to  determine  or 
to  check  in  himself,  the  community  may  create  or 
prevent  by  the  means  at  its  disposal,  so  powerful  is 
their  action  on  the  individual  mind.  Society  no 
doubt  is  also  subject  to  a  determinism;  but  we  can 
clearly  see  whence,  in  decadent  communities,  in  a 
process  of  dissolution  or  morbid  evolution,  comes 
the  stimulus  or  the  check  that  these  communities  no 
longer  find  in  themselves.  In  fact  there  are  always, 

1  It  is  sufficient  here  to  point  out  the  complete  absence,  at  any  rate 
in  France,  of  asylums  for  the  treatment  of  criminals  of  limited  re- 
sponsibility, in  order  to  show  how  remote  we  are  from  the  time  when 
an  appropriate  education  will  be  given  to  degenerates  who  are  pre- 
disposed  to  criminal  action. 


SOCIAL   ACTION.  351 

side  by  side  with  communities  of  a  given  tempera- 
ment, communities  of  a  different  spirit  whose  quite 
different  future  influences  the  future  of  neighbouring 
communities.  A  nation  or  a  race  exercises  its  happy 
or  unhappy  influence  on  another  nation  or  on  another 
race,  and'  there  is  an  incessant  overlapping  of  actions 
and  reactions  between  the  different  societies  in  the 
world;  and  this  causes  social  determinism  to  differ  in 
other  respects  from  the  inevitableness  which  involves 
an  irremediable  collective  decadence. 

Hence  for  individuals  there  are  remedies  and  pre- 
ventives of  social  origin,  just  as  there  are  remedies 
and  preventives  for  families,  cities,  and  nations  in 
the  wider  communities  of  which  these  elementary 
communities  form  a  part.  (For  this  subject  vide  my 
treatise  on  the  social  causes  of  insanity,  a  criticism  of 
too  narrow  a  conception  of  sociological  degeneration.) 
Now  if  there  are  incurable  criminals,  there  is 
no  social  incurability.  Humanity  can  amend  itself 
indefinitely  by  destroying  in  its  midst  all  the  social 
causes  of  mental  insanity,  of  moral  insanity,  of 
psychological  debility,  and  of  instability  or  morbid 
stability  of  the  mind.  No  doubt  a  collectivity  cannot 
move  more  rapidly  than  the  present  state  of  its 
civilisation  permits.  The  moralising  power  that  it 
may  exercise  over  itself  is  certainly  limited;  but  it 
can  make  no  mistake  when  there  is  an  increase  in- 
stead of  a  progressive  decrease  of  criminality  and 
immorality.  When  there  is  an  increase  in  the 
number  and  the  importance  of  misdemeanours  and 
crimes,  we  may  fearlessly  assert  the  very  wide 
responsibility  of  society  with  regard  to  individual 
faults. 

The  question  is  how  to  find  out  what  remedies 


352  SANCTION    AND    MORAL    EDUCATION. 

and  preventives  of  social  origin  will  have  an  effect 
on  criminals  or  delinquents, — if  not  on  all,  at  least 
on  most  of  them,  and  certainly  on  a  special  category 
of  social  beings. 

II. 

SANCTION    AND   MORAL   EDUCATION. 

169.  The  Role  and  Nature  of  Sanction. 

SINCE  men  come  to  a  decision  under  the  influence 
of  sentiments  much  more  than  of  the  conclusions 
of  pure  reason,  and  since  there  must  always  be 
with  the  directing  idea  a  rather  strong  tendency  to 
make  the  idea  effectively  directing,  to  such  a  point 
that  the  keenest  intelligence  can  do  nothing  for  the 
morality  of  an  agent  when  his  sentiments  are  bad 
and  irremediably  low, — since  this  is  so,  it  is  quite  fair 
to  appeal  to  means  drawn  from  the  psychology  of 
the  sentiments  to  give  to  the  civil  law  a  power  over 
the  mind,  a  power  which  it  does  not  hold  from  the 
simple  enunciation  of  the  prescription. 

Thus  all  legislatures  have  sanctioned  rules  of  con- 
duct which  they  promulgate  by  penal  dispositions 
involving  pain  to  the  delinquent  in  the  case  of  non- 
observation  of  the  law.  The  fear  of  pain  has  seemed 
from  all  time  to  be  the  most  efficacious  motive  that 
it  is  possible  to  awaken  in  the  mind  of  man  with  a 
view  to  the  accomplishment  of  his  social  duties. 

Ipso  facto  the  idea  of  sanction  has  been  intimately 
associated  with  that  of  pain  or  its  contrary — reward. 
However,  it  is  possible  to  arouse  other  motives 
than  the  desire  of  reward  or  the  fear  of  punishment. 


THE  R6LE  AND  NATURE  OF  SANCTION.    353 

According  to  circumstances  we  may  appeal  to  the 
aesthetic,  family,  or  civic  sentiments,  to  sympathetic 
emotions,  and  to  generous  tendencies.  The  law  may 
present  itself  together  with  considerations  capable  of 
stirring  the  heart  and  of  impressing  that  law  pro- 
foundly on  the  mind.  It  may  be  reinforced  in  its 
authority  by  the  respect  that  is  inspired  by  its  very 
origin;  instead  of  being  a  simple  prescription,  often 
apparently  arbitrary,  it  may  be  presented  as  the  very 
consequence  of  certain  effective  desires. 

In  fact,  laws  are  generally  respected  because  of  the 
fear  inspired  by  the  thought  of  reprisals,  exercised 
by  the  chief  or  the  caste  which  issued  the  rules  of 
common  conduct.  Men  have  governed  men  as  they 
govern  animals,  much  more  by  force  than  by  per- 
suasion. Besides,  pain  has  another  origin  than  the 
desire  of  sanctioning  a  la\v;  punishment  and  crime 
existed  before  written  law  and  judicial  forms.  The 
breaking  of  traditions,  acts  opposed  to  prejudices, 
customs,  and  to  the  tendencies  of  primitive  people, 
all  involved  violent  reactions  of  the  multitude 
against  the  individual.  Death  frequently  followed 
the  slightest  breach  of  the  tacit  prescriptions  of  a 
people  or  of  a  caste. 

The  rigour  of  penal  reactions  seems  to  us  to  de- 
crease in  the  course  of  civilisation.  Stoning  to  death 
has  disappeared.  Lynching  tends  to  disappear,  and, 
among  all  civilised  races,  is  no  longer  considered  as 
anything  but  collective  crime.  But  the  State,  sub- 
stituting itself  for  the  impulsive,  blind,  and  unjust 
mob,  prone  to  every  kind  of  excess,  has  given  to 
pain  the  character  of  impulsive  reaction  wrhich  it 
has  joined  to  that  of  legal  sanction;  hence  has 
followed  a  constant  confusion  in  the  conception  of 

23 


354  SANCTION    AND    MORAL    EDUCATION. 

the  part  that  pain  should  play.  Punishment  has 
been  considered  as  a  means  of  reparation,  as  a 
necessary  consequence  of  crime,  just  as  reward 
would  .be  considered  the  necessary  consequence  of 
merit. 

Kant  would  attribute  all  the  energy  of  this  belief 
in  the  necessity  of  reward  or  punishment  to  the 
consequence  of  good  or  evil  action.  He  does  not  think 
that  the  fear  of  punishment  or  the  hope  of  reward  is 
a  motive  to  virtuous  action  ;  but  he  considers  almost 
as  an  a  priori  synthetic  proposition  the  assertion  that 
vice  should  be  punished  and  virtue  rewarded. 

No  opinion  could  be  more  arbitrary.  Nowhere 
perhaps  in  morality  is  more  clearly  to  be  seen  the 
influence  of  long  tradition  on  the  concepts  of  prac- 
tical reason.  Because  an  impulsive  reaction,  cruel 
or  kind,  favourable  or  unfavourable,  has  always 
followed  in  partially  civilised  humanity  the  action 
that  is  considered  criminal,  or  the  action  considered 
good  (that  is  to  say,  contrary  to,  or  in  conformity 
with,  the  beliefs  and  prejudices  of  the  multitude),  we 
therefore  believe  in  the  rational  necessity  of  such 
a  sequence  of  facts,  and  claim  to  make  of  God  the 
fittest  means  to  realise  this  so-called  supreme  end : 
the  correspondence  of  happiness  and  virtue,  of  suffer- 
ing and  vice. 

M.  Paul  Janet  has  tried  to  justify  this  conception 
by  basing  it  on  the  idea  of  distributive  justice.  From 
the  moment  that  good  and  evil  may  be  apportioned 
to  man,  it  is  right  that  they  should  be  distributed 
proportionately  to  the  merits  and  according  to  the 
moral  value  of  each.  But  there  is  a  preliminary 
question :  is  there,  outside  the  good  which  the 
aptitude  of  each  to  secure  it  for  himself  submits 


THE    CONSEQUENCE    OF    MORAL    ACTION.         355 

to  an  equitable  redivision,  other  goods  which  are 
independent  of  technical  aptitudes,  as  far  as  their 
acquisition  is  concerned  ?  If  so — if,  for  example,  there 
were  reason  for  admitting  the  existence  after  death 
of  a  life  in  which  joy  would  be  granted  in  a  measure 
wide,  or  average,  or  slight,  we  conceive  that  distri- 
butive justice  requires  the  redivision  of  this  good 
according  to  moral  merit.  But  in  our  present  ex- 
istence we  see  that  happiness,  if  it  is  not  always 
acquired  by  moral  virtue,  is  in  general  obtained  by 
those  wrho  are  skilful  in  procuring  their  own  advan- 
tage. It  is  not  true  that  the  good  are  always  un- 
happy, and  especially  is  it  not  true  that  moral  value 
is  doomed  never  to  procure  real  happiness  by  its  own 
efforts  on  earth. 


170.  Happiness  the  Natural  Consequence  oj  Moral 
A  ction. 

No  doubt  we  do  not  content  ourselves  with  the 
satisfaction  procured  by  duty  accomplished.  The 
Stoics  were  wrong  in  believing  that  virtue  \vas  its 
own  reward,  and  in  considering  all  material  good,  all 
other  joys  than  purely  moral  joys,  as  indifferent. 
Happiness,  from  wherever  it  may  spring,  is  to  be 
esteemed  and  to  be  desired,  provided  it  is  not  in- 
jurious to  individual  or  social  perfection.  The  moral 
being  may  lawfully  claim  his  share  of  pleasure,  his 
share  of  material  well-being,  and  of  intellectual, 
aesthetic,  and  social  satisfaction. 

Why  then  does  he  not  sometimes  obtain  it  ?  Is  it 
not  because,  in  spite  of  his  excellent  intentions,  he 
does  not  succeed  in  playing  the  part  which  might 
procure  for  him  the  satisfactions  which  he  is  entitled 


35^  SANCTION    AND    MORAL    EDUCATION. 

to  desire  ?  We  are  wrong  if  we  separate  skill  from 
integrity.  It  will  be  sufficient  to  distinguish  between 
those  who  are  skilful  without  being  honourable,  and 
those  who  are  both  honourable  and  skilful,  that  is  to 
say,  those  who  can  find  the  means  best  fitted  for  the 
realisation  of  their  moral  ends,  who  discover  imme- 
diately how  inferior  is  integrity  without  skill,  although 
that  is  preferable  to  skill  without  morality. 

To  be  a  moral  being  we  need  not  be  an  innocent 
being,  a  dupe  or  a  victim.  All  we  ask  is  to  be  a 
being  of  our  own  time  and  environment,  no  doubt  so 
as  to  be  a  factor  of  progress  for  one's  environment, 
but  also  so  that  we  may  adapt  ourselves  to  the  con- 
ditions of  existence  in  which  we  are  placed.  If  a 
virtuous  man  living  a  solitary  life  is  ignorant  of  a 
series  of  joys  which  are  well  known  to  the  wicked,  he 
can  only  blame  himself  for  his  inferiority  from  the 
point  of  view  of  happiness.  If,  instead  of  hoping  for 
reward  in  a  future  life  in  return  for  the  privations 
which  he  endures  in  his  present  existence,  he  would 
force  himself  all  the  more  to  become  a  social  being, 
useful  to  his  fellows,  in  solidarity  with  his  fellow- 
citizens,  he  would  be  in  solidarity  with  them  in  . 
pleasure  as  well  as  in  pain ;  and  he  would  very  soon 
perceive  that  if  in  the  present  social  system  it  fre- 
quently happens  that  the  ungodly  triumph  and  that 
the  good  suffer,  the  fault  often  lies  with  the  good 
who  do  not  know  how  to  work  on  behalf  of  collective 
virtue. 

When  one  is  too  engrossed  to  acquire  private 
virtues,  which  can  only  have  value  in  so  far  as  they 
are  a  condition  of  public  virtues ;  when  we  deliberately 
forget  our  fellows  and  only  think  of  our  own  perfec- 
tion, we  are  punished  by  the  doom  of  the  ages — the 


THE    CONSEQUENCE    OF   MORAL   ACTION.         357 

unhappiness  of  the  good  amid  the  happiness  of  the 
wicked. 

It  is  then  because  the  good  are  not  good  enough 
that  they  are  unhappy.  It  is  because  their  goodness 
is  too  passive,  their  virtue  not  sufficiently  active,  that 
they  see  happiness  flee  from  them.  They  have  not 
sufficiently  deserved  it. 

All  the  efforts  of  social  beings  ought  to  tend  to  the 
realisation  of  a  social  order  from  which  injustice  is 
progressively  eliminated,  in  which  the  harmful  effects 
of  wickedness  are  more  or  less  attenuated,  in  which 
the  scale  of  moral  values,  which  is  in  addition  the 
scale  of  social  values  when  it  is  a  question  of  persons, 
corresponds  exactly  to  the  scale  of  good  and  pleasure. 

What  is  there  more  natural  than  to  see  health 
procured  by  temperance,  regularity  of  employment 
and  well-being  procured  by  professional  skill,  esteem 
and  honours  resulting  from  persevering  integrity,  and 
from  the  affection  and  the  devotion  of  one's  fellows 
—which  are  the  reward  of  services  rendered  to  the 
common  cause,  and  therefore  to  individual  causes. 
What  is  it,  then,  which  prevents  the  moral  man  from 
being  happy  ?  Accidents,  social  disturbance,  physi- 
cal and  moral  contagion — in  short,  the  effects  of 
fortuitous  occurrences  due  to  the  complexity  of  social 
relations  and  the  effects  of  universal  solidarity.  But 
man  becomes  more  and  more  the  master  of  nature 
and  eliminates  the  disastrous  consequences  of  that 
chance  of  which  the  ancients  made  a  God,  because  it 
was  more  dreaded  by  them  than  by  us ;  and  more 
and  more  also  does  moral  solidarity,  the  voluntary 
consensus  of  reasonable  beings,  replace  the  primitive 
solidarity,  which  was  certainly  more  dangerous  than 
productive  of  moral  results. 


SANCTION    AND    MORAL    EDUCATION. 

The  optimism  to  which  we  may  abandon  ourselves 
has  nothing  in  common  with  theological  or  meta- 
physical optimism ;  it  is  not  based  on  subjective 
beliefs  or  on  an  arbitrary  conception  of  the  world. 
Facts  are  its  foundation — the  progress  of  science 
and  the  progress  of  intelligent  solidarity.  We  may 
therefore  hope  that  by  incessant  effort  (for  moral 
optimism  far  from  enervating  and  weakening,  far 
from  giving  confidence  to  the  idle  who  might  trust 
in  an  inevitable  evolution,  excites  the  energies  and 
stimulates  to  action),  by  a  persistent  desire  to  realise  a 
social  system  which  becomes  more  and  more  unified, 
we  shall  eventually  bring  into  agreement  both  nature 
and  morality,  and  secure  happiness  for  the  good. 

But,  once  more,  the  acquisition  of  happiness  will 
be  the  natural  consequence  of  the  skill  exhibited,  of 
the  ability  with  which  the  moral  being  will  reach  his 
ends.  It  will  not  therefore  be  a  sanction  in  the  sense 
in  which  sanction  was  understood  by  classical  philo- 
sophy. It  will  be  rather  what  is  sometimes  under- 
stood by  "  natural  sanction."  It  is  far  better  simply 
to  say  that  this  will  be  a  natural  result  of  increasing 
morality. 

In  the  same  way  the  suffering  which  will  result  to 
the  unskilful  and  the  dishonest,  from  the  privation  of 
the  good  and  the  pleasure  that  a  more  systematic 
conduct  would  have  certainly  secured  for  them,  will 
not  be  a  sanction  or  a  punishment,  but  the  simple 
result  of  their  immorality  in  the  midst  of  increasing 
morality. 

171.  Merit. 

The  ideas  of  merit  and  demerit  have  only  a 
relation  to  the  natural  consequences  of  good  or  evil 


MERIT.  359 

action  in  so  far  as  we  can  imagine  a  social  state 
different  from  that  in  which  the  agent  resides,  a  social 
state  ensuring  results  the  best  adapted  to  the  import- 
ance of  the  cause.  We  may  be  convinced  that  man 
will  always  imagine  a  social  organisation  superior  to 
that  which  he  enjoys.  The  idea  of  the  Elysian 
Fields  and  of  Paradise,  as  ancient  perhaps  as  man 
himself,  is  far  from  disappearing  from  the  human 
consciousness.  At  most  it  may  be  secularised,  and 
become  the  idea  of  a  physical  and  social  environ- 
ment, more  in  conformity  to  the  moral  ideal.  So 
that  if  we  no  longer  conceive  the  man  of  high  moral 
value  as  deserving  greater  pleasure  in  heaven,  he  will 
be  conceived  as  deserving  it  in  a  better  terrestrial 
world.  As  for  the  wicked,  he  will  be  considered  less 
and  less  worthy  to  live  in  this  better  world;  and  just 
as  in  our  days  the  Catholic  generally  expels  him  from 
heaven  and  plunges  him  into  hell,  so,  perhaps,  lay 
opinion  will  claim  to  expel  him  from  the  society  of 
the  future.  But  these  are  only  the  very  natural  con- 
sequences of  the  conception  of  an  ideal  of  common 
life.  To  deserve  to  be  admitted  into  the  Republic 
of  Plato,  or  into  the  city  of  God  or  into  a  future 
humanity,  there  to  enjoy  the  pleasure  of  the  wise  and 
the  happiness  of  the  virtuous  being,  is  the  desire  of 
the  moral  being  who  works  for  the  realisation  of  this 
ideal  of  collective  existence.  Not  to  deserve  it  is  the 
characteristic  of  the  wicked,  who  does  not  trouble 
his  head  about  such  a  realisation. 

Does  not  this  go  far  to  realise  the  classical  theory, 
according  to  which  to  every  moral  act  must  be  added 
a  reward,  and  to  every  immoral  act  a  punishment  ? 
according  to  which  the  good  deserves  to  be  rewarded 
beyond  the  natural  consequences  of  his  good  action, 


360  SANCTION    AND    MORAL    EDUCATION. 

and  the  wicked  deserves  to  suffer  beyond  the  suffering 
that  his  misdoing  may  naturally  cause  to  him  ? 


172.  The  Immorality  of  Punishment. 

Is  it  not  even  immoral  and  inhuman  to  assert  that 
the  sum  of  suffering  which  weighs  upon  humanity 
must  be  increased  by  punishments  ?  How  can  the 
death  of  a  criminal  and  the  tortures  inflicted  upon 
him  be  moral  ?  Is  it  not  a  relic  of  barbarism  to 
conceive  of  the  pain  of  the  delinquent  as  well 
deserved  ?  And  besides,  what  is  this  multitude  which 
crowds  around  the  foot  of  the  scaffold  and  claps  its 
hands,  and  laughs,  and  sings  when  the  knife  falls  ? 
Is  it  not  the  ignoble  mob  issuing  from  the  low 
quarters  of  our  great  towns,  bearing  all  the  stigmata 
of  degeneration,  and  exhibiting  a  well-marked  rever- 
sion to  the  most  brutal  ancestral  type,  in  our 
civilised  eyes  the  most  monstrous  type  of  all  ? 
Should  we  not  therefore  be  ashamed  of  ourselves 
when  the  old  leaven  of  animal  cruelty  gives  rise  in 
us  to  thoughts  and  sentiments  of  reprisal  with 
respect  to  the  criminal,  and  when  our  heart  is 
not  touched  by  the  sufferings  inflicted  upon  the 
delinquent  ? 

To  make  him  suffer  who  has  made  others  suffer, 
to  be  cruel  towards  the  man  who  has  been  cruel, 
is  to  multiply  the  wrong  instead  of  healing  the 
wound.  It  is  adding  to  the  individual  fault  a  social 
fault,  and  putting  the  criminal  in  the  position  of  a 
man  on  whom  vile  vengeance  is  taken.1  Let  the  man 
who  has  done  the  wrong  help  to  repair  it.  Let  him 
make  good  the  public  and  private  mischief  that  he 

1  Cf-  A.  France,  Les  Idees  de  J.  Coignard. 


UTILITARIAN    ROLE    OF    PUNISHMENT.  361 

has  caused.  That  is  the  principle  of  contractual 
justice  which  tends  to  prevail  in  our  days,  because 
obligations  tend  to  become  more  and  more  exact 
now  that  they  are  stipulated  in  contracts.  There 
always  are  cases  in  which  the  public  injury  caused  by 
a  criminal  cannot  be  estimated.  Violation  of  the 
law  is  much  more  pernicious  because  it  tends  to  the 
destruction  of  the  social  edifice,  than  because  it  in- 
volves injury  that  may  be  valued.  Therefore  wre 
must  endeavour  above  all  to  prevent  the  tendency  to 
violate  the  law  and  the  moral  precept  from  being 
generalised,  for  this  would  render  social  life  im- 
possible. 

173.   Utilitarian  Role  of  Punishment. 

Perhaps  then  punishment  may  be  really  a  sanction, 
that  is  to  say,  the  means  of  reinforcing  the  influence 
of  the  law  on  the  mind  of  him  who  deliberates, 
chooses,  and  acts.  By  arousing  in  the  mind  the 
fear  of  punishment  we  create  a  new  motive  to  action 
or  inhibition ;  but  this  sanction,  which  is  purely 
utilitarian,  is  the  last  means  to  which  society  can 
have  recourse  to  influence  or  restrain  the  individual. 
It  is  the  complement  of  an  insufficient  education  or 
an  education  which  has  not  brought  forth  all  its 
fruit. 

It  is  therefore  important  that  punishment  should 
be  inflicted  only  if  its  influence  will  be  effective  on 
the  mind  of  the  subject  who  deliberates,  and  that 
only  that  kind  of  punishment  should  be  inflicted 
which  will  exercise  an  effective  influence  on  a  given 
mind. 

If  this  be  done  the  punishment  of  the  insane  will 
cease,  because  they  are  incapable  of  reflection ;  and  so 


362  SANCTION    AND    MORAL    EDUCATION. 

with  idiots,  who  are  imbeciles  incapable  of  action 
with  a  motive,  not  so  much  because  they  are  not 
responsible  or  because  fault  is  not  imputable  to 
them,  but  because  no  sanction  has  any  influence  on 
them. 

The  child  who  has  committed  a  fault  through 
bewilderment,  the  young  man,  the  adult,  the  old 
man,  who  have  let  themselves  be  dragged  into 
crime  through  impulse,  and  have  thereby  shown  that 
they  lack  an  inner  restraint  and  sufficient  power  of 
self-control,  profit  by  the  punishment  that  is  inflicted 
upon  them.  As  for  the  morally  insane,  who  commit 
voluntary  crimes,  who  accomplish  the  most  abomin- 
able acts  with  the  greatest  sang  froid — and  that,  as 
we  have  seen,  from  lack  of  lofty  sentiments,  from  a 
pathological  absence  of  tendencies  to  social  life — it 
may  sometimes  be  useful,  and  even  absolutely  neces- 
sary, that  the  civil  or  moral  law  should  appear  to 
them  to  be  sanctioned,  and  that  its  violation  should 
be  conceived  of  by  them  as  eminently  disastrous. 

How  many  people  are  there  in  the  most  civilised 
society  without  fear  of  police  or  prison,  and  who, 
because  they  lack  generous  tendencies  and  noble 
sentiments,  let  themselves  drift  into  excess,  im- 
morality, misdemeanour,  and  crime  ?  They  are 
like  the  morally  insane  in  the  sense  that  they 
lack  certain  inclinations  characteristic  of  the  moral 
being,  although  they  differ  from  the  delinquent  or 
criminal  lunatic  in  the  sense  that  their  impulses  or 
obsessions  do  not  so  inevitably  issue  in  the  doing  of 
wrong.  In  number  they  are  legion,  and  that  is  why 
it  seems  that  fear,  the  only  motive  capable  of  exer- 
cising an  effective  influence  on  their  voluntary 
decisions,  must  be  inspired  in  most  human  beings 


UTILITARIAN    ROLE    OF    PUNISHMENT.  363 

by  the  establishment  of  punishments  sanctioning 
the  laws. 

Does  this  imply  that  a  haunting  dread  is  the  sole 
instrument  by  which  respect  for  the  laws  and  the 
doing  of  one's  duty  is  wholly  and  always  to  be 
impressed  on  humanity  ?  Does  it  mean  that  the  fear 
of  the  police,  or  that  the  fear  of  the  Lord,  will  be 
the  last  word  of  the  wisdom  of  multitudes  ? 

If  the  former,  we  must  teach  the  people  that  the 
most  terrible  punishments  in  this  world  and  the  next 
await  the  delinquent,  or  we  must  at  any  rate  attach 
to  virtue  so  many  rewards  and  to  vice  such  punish- 
ment that  appetite  and  fear  will  become  the  most 
powerful  motives  to  human  actions.  This  means  a 
real  "morality  of  slaves";  it  means  that  fear  must 
dominate  man. 

But  is  fear  a  normal  sentiment  ?  Is  it  not  one 
of  those  pathological  sentiments  which  disturb  the 
intellect  and  paralyse  action.  If  we  undertake  to 
establish  a  morality  having  as  its  end  the  normal 
functioning  of  the  psycho-sociological  being  we  ought 
only  to  provisionally  admit  an  abnormal  mental  state. 

Now  the  effects  of  dread  are  known.  Those  of  fear 
are  none  the  less  known.  It  is  sufficient  to  see  the 
habitual  attitude  and  the  state  of  heart  and  mind  to 
which  young  people  are  brought  who  are  subject  to 
a  terrible  discipline,  to  be  under  no  illusion  as  to  the 
value  of  a  morality  that  is  based  on  dread.  The 
man  who  fears  is  either  a  being  resigned  to  apathy, 
or  a  sly  creature,  a  secret  rebel,  who  only  waits  for 
a  favourable  opportunity  to  escape  the  obligations 
imposed  upon  him  by  a  master  whom  he  hates.  As 
M.  Richard1  has  said,  the  State  progresses  by 

1   Rev.  Phil.,  1899,  t.  ii.,  pp.  475  et  set/. 


364  SANCTION    AND    MORAL    EDUCATION. 

economising  constraint  and  by  soliciting  the  obedi- 
ence of  the  individual  to  the  requirements  of  col- 
lective life,  appealing  to  other  motives  than  fear. 
There  is  a  general  tendency  to  avoid  imprisoning 
children  capable  of  improvement.  In  England  we 
send  them  to  Reformatory  Schools,  in  France  to 
Houses  of  Correction,  which  are  unfortunately  too 
badly  organised  to  give  happy  results.  The  law  of 
reprieve  is  inspired  by  a  wise  mistrust  of  the  fatal 
consequences  of  imprisonment  and  by  a  belief,  which 
has  been  proved  justified,  in  the  happy  effects  of  a 
severe  warning.  Let  the  prison  of  the  near  future  be 
transformed  into  an  asylum  for  the  moral  health. 
We  have  seen  that  responsibility  for  crime  is  made 
incumbent  on  a  nature  that  has  been  given  to  the 
delinquent,  on  a  character  which  can  only  be 
reformed  by  the  very  person  who  acted,  and  can 
only  act,  according  to  his  own  character;  thus  the 
criminal,  the  delinquent,  and  the  immoral  being  are 
defective  beings. 

Society  should  defend  itself  against  their  attacks 
without  anger,  and  protect  itself  as  it  would  against 
the  possible  wrong-doing  of  a  dog,  a  horse,  or  any  of 
our  "  inferior  brethren."  To  prevent  the  repetition 
of  crimes  and  misdemeanours  which  have  been  com- 
mitted in  spite  of  preventive  measures,  we  must  first 
of  all  prevent  the  evil-doer  from  continuing  to  set  a 
bad  example — just  as  we  should  prevent  an  epileptic 
from  falling  too  frequently  into  his  crises  in  the 
presence  of  hysterical  subjects,  who  would  be  only 
too  ready  to  imitate  him.  We  must  therefore  take 
pains  with  the  delinquent  and  not  restore  him  to. 
liberty  until  he  is  cured,  until  he  has  lessened  the 
violence  of  his  passions  or  the  power  of  his  disastrous 


UTILITARIAN    R6LE    OF    PUNISHMENT.  365 

tendencies,  until  he  has  really  grown  wiser  and  has 
not  been  brought,  as  happens  too  often,  to  a  state  of 
mere  hypocrisy  by  ill  treatment  and  by  fear.  Let  us 
not  forget  that  all  minds  are  not  accessible  to  fear. 
In  the  first  place,  there  are  degenerates  whom  no 
punishment  can  terrify,  and  who  experience  a  kind  of 
pleasure  in  bearing  the  chastisement  and  the  humili- 
ation which  would  cause  in  others  bitter  pangs. 
There  are  also  strong  men,  courageous  men,  whom 
fear  and  suffering  cannot  check,  and  to  whom  pun- 
ishment cannot  constitute  a  sanction  qualified  to  re- 
inforce the  power  of  the  law.  In  such  people  quite 
different  sentiments  must  be  evoked  if  we  wish  to 
determine  them  to  moral  conduct.  To  some  the 
awakening  of  an  appetite,  to  others  conformity  of 
action  to  a  strong  tendency,  will  be  sufficiently 
powerful  a  feeling  or  end  to  determine  the  suit- 
able choice.  Educators  know  it  well.  Each  child 
must  be  attacked  on  his  "  sensitive  side "  to  bring 
him  to  what  we  desire.  Adults  are  for  the  most  part 
but  great  children.  "  Trahit  sua  quemque  voluptas " 
was  said  by  one  who  did  not  realise  perhaps  the 
distinction  that  should  be  drawn  from  the  practical 
point  of  view  between  the  pleasure  which  is  not 
alwrays  proposed  as  an  end,  and  the  desire  which  is 
always  a  motive,  even  when  it  is  not  the  desire  of 
enjoyment,  even  when  its  satisfaction  involves  suffer- 
ing. The  real  meaning  of  the  aphorism  is  this — each 
of  us  is  led  by  his  own  inclinations.  We  must  there- 
fore recognise  the  inclinations  characteristic  of  each 
of  those  whose  conduct  we  desire  to  direct,  in  order 
to  ascertain  what  are  the  inclinations  whose  develop- 
ment may  be  useful  to  the  development  of  morality, 
and  to  endeavour  to  give  to  the  moral  prescription 


366  SANCTION    AND    MORAL    EDUCATION. 

the  support  which  would  be  absent  if  those  inclina- 
tions were,  so  to  speak,  only  "skin  deep."  Far 
from  skimming  over  the  surface  of  the  consciousness, 
moral  law  should  penetrate  it;  and  there  is  no  other 
means  of  penetrating  a  mind  than  the  natural  path 
traced  out  by  the  tendencies,  the  inclinations,  and 
the  appetites.  Punishment  and  reward  are  means  of 
superficial  action  which  can  only  disturb  the  con- 
sciousness by  the  impetus  of  the  shock.  It  is  not 
by  them  that  prohibitions  or  prescriptions  are 
insinuated  into  the  mind.  On  the  contrary,  habit 
dulls  the  sensibility  to  those  sanctions  because  they 
are  mainly  external. 

M.  Enrico  Ferri1  rightly  says  that  "the  experi- 
ence of  daily  life  in  the  family,  in  the  school,  and  in 
the  social  group,  as  well  as  the  history  of  social  life, 
show  that  to  render  less  pernicious  the  outburst  of 
the  passions,  it  is  far  better  to  take  them  in  flank  and 
at  their  origin  than  to  attack  them  in  front.  To 
preserve  his  wife's  fidelity  the  astute  husband  counts 
on  many  other  considerations  than  the  regulations  of 
the  penal  code  against  adultery.  .  .  .  Inattention 
and  tendencies  to  destruction  in  the  child  are  much 
better  restrained  by  well-adapted  games  than  by  a 
punishment  which  has  failed  to  repress  them.  .  .  . 
That  is  why  experience  shows  in  the  judicial-criminal 
domain  that  punishments  fail  completely  in  the  end, 
which  is  entirely  one  of  social  defence,  so  that  we 
must  have  recourse  to  other  means  of  satisfying  the 
requirements  of  social  order.  Hence  what  I  have 
called  'penal  substitutes'  (sostitutivi  penali}"  The 
conception  of  "  substitutes "  for  punishment  is 
summed  up  as  follows :  The  legislature,  after 

1  Sociologia  criminate^  pp.  395  et  seq. 


MORAL    SUGGESTION.  367 

having  examined  the  varied  aspects  and  manifesta- 
tions of  the  individual  and  social  activity,  after 
having  discovered  the  origin,  the  conditions,  and  the 
consequences  of  criminal  facts,  after  learning  the 
psychological  and  sociological  laws  which,  in  a  great 
part  at  any  rate,  give  the  reason  of  them,  ought  to 
endeavour  to  exercise  a  felicitous  influence  on  the 
processus  of  criminality.  For  that  purpose  the  social 
organism  should  receive  such  an  orientation  that 
human  activity  instead  of  being  uselessly  threatened 
with  repression  may  be  guided  in  a  continuous  and 
indirect  manner  towards  non-criminal  objects,  by 
offering  the  freest  possible  course  to  individual 
energies  and  ends,  but  avoiding  as  much  as  possible 
temptations  and  opportunities  for  crime. 

174.  Moral  Suggestion. 

With  respect  to  most  people  we  must  act  as  with 
respect  to  delinquents;  and  to  prevent  the  former 
from  engaging  in  vice  we  must  use  the  processes 
that  are  employed  to  prevent  the  latter  from  falling 
back  into  crime.  As  we  give  up  the  idea  of  inspiring 
them  with  the  fear  of  punishment,  we  must  accept 
the  obligation  of  giving  them  a  moral  education. 

Now  we  must  be  sure  that  the  moralising  action 
is  exercised  not  by  speech,  command,  or  prohibition, 
but  by  suggestion  which  varies  with  the  individual, 
and  differs  in  its  nature  according  to  the  character 
appropriate  to  each  case  and  corresponding  to 
particular  tendencies.  If  a  child  or  a  man  has  more 
marked  aesthetic  than  scientific  tendencies,  do  not 
idly  preach  to  him  the  love  of  science  which  would 
lead  another  man  by  the  cult  of  the  true  to  very 


368  SANCTION    AND    MORAL    EDUCATION. 

lofty  social  and  moral  sentiments.  Let  us  show 
him  the  neighbouring  road  which  passes  from  the 
beautiful  to  the  good;  let  us  excite  his  aesthetic 
sentiments  until  he  desires  to  see  beauty  in  conduct, 
and  harmony  both  in  his  acts  and  in  the  totality 
formed  by  his  acts  and  those  of  his  fellows. 
Let  each  character  retain  its  peculiar  aspect,  and 
for  that  purpose  preserve  its  characteristic  tendencies. 
It  will  none  the  less  be  normal  and  moral;  for 
virtue  may  be  attained  by  many  ways  as  long  as 
these  tendencies  do  not  exclude  certain  sentiments 
which  are  indispensable  to  morality. 

Hence,  to  penetrate  into  the  heart  of  a  man,  let  us 
study  his  character  and  adapt  our  method  of  acting 
to  his  requirements.  Let  us  understand  him  well  in 
order  that  in  his  turn  he  may  enjoy  with  us  a  unity 
of  ideas  and  sentiments.  If  we  wish  to  educate  a 
weak-minded  person,  the  best  thing  is  first  to  leave 
him  in  the  company  of  good  comrades,  who,  without 
trying  to  attract  him  by  benefits  or  kindnesses,  little 
by  little  determine  in  him  sympathies  and  antipathies. 
He  attaches  himself  to  the  most  sympathetic,  follows 
him,  imitates  him,  is  devoted  to  him,  and  obeys  him 
just  as  a  hypnotised  person  is  dominated  by  his 
magnetiser.  Thus  is  exercised  moral  suggestion; 
and  it  is  the  more  powerful  in  proportion  as  the 
sympathy  inspired  in  the  patient  by  his  companion 
is  great. 

Imitation  springs  from  sympathy,  or  rather  blends 
with  it;  for  sympathy  results  from  spontaneous 
imitation,  which  is  rendered  easy  by  the  affinities 
of  two  characters.  The  two  phenomena  react  on 
and  mutually  strengthen  each  other.  By  spontaneous 
imitation  one  is  subjected  to  the  thraldom  of  custom, 


MORAL    SUGGESTION.  369 

of  fashion,  and  manners.  Through  it  we  acquire 
methods  of  thinking,  feeling,  and  acting,  which  are 
strange  or  foreign  in  their  origin,  and  which  are 
assimilated  the  more  easily  according  as  they  meet 
with  fewer  antagonisms  in  the  mind  that  receives 
them.  Now  the  power  of  antagonistic  sentiments 
may  be  reduced  beforehand  by  slow  pressure  exer- 
cised by  the  skilful  teacher,  so  that  the  path  is  made 
clear  for  new  tendencies. 

Young  people  whose  sentiments  are  not  yet  fixed 
and  are  not  yet  completely  developed  are  particularly 
apt  to  receive  moral  suggestions  both  negative  and 
positive,  exercised  in  the  direction  of  restraint  or 
in  that  of  the  exaltation  of  certain  sentiments. 
That  is  why  people  anxious  about  their  moral  future 
have  always  confided  the  education  of  youth  to  those 
who  have  the  same  ideal  as  the  great  majority  of  the 
citizens  in  the  midst  of  whom  they  fill  the  important 
part  of  suggesters.  The  wisest  of  the  Greeks  and 
Romans  kept  their  children  as  far  as  possible  from 
educators  like  the  Sophists  and  the  Academicians, 
skilful  as  they  were  to  capture  the  intellect,  but 
far  too  hostile  to  the  virtues  which  Greece  and 
Rome  had  learned  to  esteem.  Modern  races  should 
show  the  same  care  to  preserve  their  young  people 
from  morbid  suggestions,  which  are  fatal  to  social 
harmony  and  to  the  realisation  of  a  collective  ideal. 

In  fact,  the  happy  choice  of  the  educators  of  youth 
is  a  condition  of  moral  safety  to  the  country;  the 
future  depends  upon  it;  and  not  only  the  future  of 
those  who  have  been  subject  to  moral  or  immoral 
suggestion,  not  only  the  future  of  their  whole  genera- 
tion, but  also  the  future  of  successive  generations, 
which  will  grow  up  in  a  social  environment  in  which 

24 


370  SANCTION    AND    MORAL    EDUCATION. 

certain  sentiments  indispensable  to  morality  will  be 
developed,  or  will  be  stifled  as  soon  as  they  appear. 
For  the  whole  of  the  people  act  on  each  individual 
as  a  skilful  teacher.  In  this  totality  each  being  finds 
a  more  or  less  considerable  number  of  citizens  with 
whom  he  is  in  sympathy,  whom  he  follows,  imitates, 
and  copies,  and  whose  manners  and  maxims  he  fully 
adopts.  This  group  of  models  must  not  form  a  sect 
which  is  opposed  to  the  neighbouring  sect  of  different 
manners.  If  education  is  one,  if  some  fundamental 
principles  remain  common  in  spite  of  the  inevitable 
divergences  which  are  due  to  diversity  of  tempera- 
ment, the  moral  unity  is  assured.  Moral  anarchy,  on 
the  contrary,  arises  from  antagonistic  morbid  sugges- 
tions, from  radically  opposed  methods  of  education. 

It  is  only  therefore  when  a  people  makes  an  effort  to 
give  to  its  youth  as  far  as  possible  the  same  education 
of  the  sentiments,  and  the  same  "  moral  suggestion," 
that  it  may  expect  to  see  a  diminution  in  the  number 
and  the  importance  of  crimes  and  faults  committed 
in  its  midst  by  individuals  or  communities. 

The  real  sanction  of  the  laws  is  in  the  morals  which 
make  their  observation  easy  and  sure.  To  give  to 
the  moral  law  and  to  moral  precepts  their  full 
authority,  they  must  penetrate  manners.  It  is  for 
moralists,  for  all  those  who  believe  they  are  in  posses- 
sion of  the  best  rules  of  conduct,  to  force  themselves, 
not  by  crying  in  the  wilderness,  but  by  acting  on 
their  environment,  to  secure  the  appearance  in  their 
country,  and  in  humanity  generally,  of  well  co- 
ordinated collective  tendencies,  of  social  causes  of 
morality,  capable  of  opposing  the  social  causes  of 

madness  and  misconduct. 

•   • 


BIBLIOGRAPHY. 


ARISTOTLE. — Nicomachaean   Ethics.     (Edit.  Acad.  of  Berlin. 

Reimer,  1831.) 
ARISTOTLE.— Politics. 
BALDWIN  (J.  M.). — Social  and  Ethical  Interpretations  in  Mental 

Development. 
BALLION  (Dr.). — La  mort  chez  les  animaux.     Bazas,  Constant, 

1900. 

BANCEL. — Le  cooperatisme.     Schleicher,  Paris,  1901. 
BELOT. — La   Religion  comme  principe  sociologique,    "  Revue 

philosophique,"  March  1900. 

BERNARD  (C.  I.).  —Lemons  sur  les  phenomenes  de  la  vie. 
BERGSEN. — Les  Donnees  immediates  de  la  conscience.     Paris, 

Alcan,  1899. 
BONCOUR   (P.). — Le  federalisme   economique.     Paris,  Alcan, 

1900. 

BOUGLE. — Les  Idees  egalitaires.     Paris,  Alcan,  1899. 
BOUTROUX.— "  Morale  sociale."     Legons  faites  au  College  des 

sciences  sociales.     Paris,  Alcan,  1899. 
BROCHARD. — La    Morale    ancienne    et    la    morale   moderne, 

"  Revue  Philosophique,"  January  1900. 
BROOKS  ADAMS.— La  loi  de  la  civilisation  et  de  la  decadence. 

Paris,  Alcan,  1899. 
BRUNSCHWICG.  —  L'ordre    des    joies,    in     "  Morale    sociale." 

Paris,  Alcan.,  1899. 
BRUNSCHWICG.— Introduction  a  la  vie  de  1'esprit.    Paris,  Alcan, 

1900. 

CHABOT.— Nature  et  moralite.     Paris,  Alcan,  1897. 
COMTE  (Aug.). — Cours  de  philosophic  positive. 
COMTE  (Aug.). — La  Sociologie  resumee  par  Rigolage.     Paris, 

Alcan,  1897. 


372  BIBLIOGRAPHY. 

COSTE.  —  L'Experience   des   peuples   et   les   provisions   qu'elle 

autorise.     Paris,  Alcan,  1900. 

CULLERRE  (Dr.). — Les  frontieres  de  la  folie.     Paris,  1888. 
DARGUN. — Ursprung  und  Entwickelungsgeschichte  der  Eigen- 

thums,  1884.     "Zeitsch.  f.  vergl.  Rechtsw.,"  Bd.  v. 
DARLU. — La  classification  des  idees  morales  du  temps  present, 

in  "Morale  sociale."     Paris,  Alcan,  1899. 
DARLU. — La  morale  chre'tienne  et  la  conscience  contemporaine, 

"Revue  de  metaph.  et  de  morale,"  1900,  p.  257. 
DELBET. — La  morale  positive.     (Ibid.} 
DELBOS. — Le  kantisme  et  la  science  de  la  morale,  "  Revue  de 

metaph.  et  de  mor.,"  March  1900. 
DUGAS. — L'amitie  antique.     Paris,  Alcan,  1896. 
DUGAS. —Analyse  psychologique  de  1'idee  de  devoir,  "Revue 

philosophique,"  1897,  t.  xliv. 
DUMONT   (Arsene). — La   Morale   basee   sur  la  demographic. 

Paris,  Schleicher,  1901. 
DURKHEIM. — La    division    du    travail    social.      Paris,   Alcan, 

1893. 

DURKHEIM. — L'Annee  sociologique,  1899-1900. 
ESPINAS.— Les  Societes  animales.     Paris,  Alcan,  1878. 
FERRI   (E.). — Sociologia    criminale.      Turin,    Bocca,   4th   ed., 

1900  (also  an  abridged  English  edition). 
FOUILLEE. — Critique  des  systemes  de  morale  contemporains. 

Paris,  Alcan,  3rd  ed.,  1893. 
FOUILLEE. — La  France  au  point  de  vue  moral.     Paris,  Alcan, 

1900. 
FRAGAPANE.— Objetto  e  limiti  della  filosofia  del  diritto.     Rome, 

Loescher,  1900. 
FRAGAPANE. — II   problema  delle  origine  del  diritto.     Rome, 

Loescher,  1896. 
FREGIER. — Des  classes  dangereuses  de  la  population  dans  les 

grandes  villes  et   des   moyens  de  les   rendre  meilleures. 

Paris,  1840. 
GOBLOT. — Essai  sur  la  classification  des  sciences.    Paris,  Alcan, 

1898. 
GRASSET   (Dr.). — La  superiorite   intellectuelle   et  la  nevrose. 

Montpellier,  Coulet,  1900. 
GUYAU. — Esquisse  d'une  morale  sans   obligation  ni  sanction. 

L'irreligion  de  1'avenir.     Paris,  Alcan,  1896. 


BIBLIOGRAPHY.  373 

JAMES    (W.).— Principles    of    Psychology.     Cf.    Marillier,    La 

psychologic  de  W.  James,  "Revue   philosophique,"  1892, 

ii.  p.  449. 

JANET  (Pierre). — L'Automatisme  psychologique.     Alcan,  1889. 
JANET  (Pierre). — Nevroses  et  idees  fixes.     Alcan,  1898. 
JANET  (Paul).— La  Morale.     Paris,  Delagrave,  5th  ed.,  1898. 
KANT. — Critique  of  Practical  Reason. 
KOVALEVSKY.— La  Morale    de  Tolstoi,  in    "Morale  Sociale." 

Paris,  Alcan,  1899. 
LALANDE. — La  dissolution  opposee  a  1'evolution.     Paris,  Alcan, 

1899. 
LAVELEYE  (de). — De  la  propriete  et  de  ses  formes  primitives. 

2nd  ed.,  Alcan,  1897. 

LEGRAIN  (Dr.). — Du  delire  chez  les  degeneres.     Paris,  1886. 
LEGRAIN   (Dr.).  — L'anthropologie   criminelle    au    Congres   de 

Bruxelles  en  1892  (extrait  de  la  "Revue  scientifique "). 
LETOURNEAU. — The   Evolution    of    Property.     Contemporary 

Science  Series. 
LICHTENBERGER.— La  Philosophic  de  Nietzsche.    Paris,  Alcan, 

1900  (4th  ed.). 
LOMBROSO. — L'Uomo  Delinquente.    French  and  German  trans. 

Turin,  Bocca,  4th  ed.,  1887. 
LOMBROSO  and  FERRERO. —  La  Donna  Delinquente.    Abridged 

English  translation,  "The  Female  Offender." 
LOURBET. — Le  probl^me  des  sexes.    Giard  et  Briere,  Paris,  1900. 
MAGNAN  (Dr.). — Lemons  cliniques  sur  les  maladies  mentales. 

Alcan,  1897. 

MALAPERT.— In  "  Morale  sociale."    Alcan,  1899. 
MARION. — Lemons  de  morale.     Paris,  A.  Colin. 
MARxl(Karl).— Salaires,  prix  et  profits.     Giard  et  Briere,  1899. 
MARX  (Karl). — Das  Capital.     English  translation. 
MAZARELLA. — La  Condizione  giuridica  del  marito  nella  famiglia 

primitiva  (matriarchalej.     Catana,  Coco,  1899. 
MILL  (John  Stuart). — Utilitarianism,     nth  ed.,  1891,  Longmans. 
MERRIAM.  —  History    of    the    Theory    of    Sovereignty    since 

Rousseau.     Columbia,  Univ.  Press,  1900. 
NIEBOER  (Dr.). — Slavery,  an  industrial  system.     The  Hague, 

1899. 

NIETZSCHE. — Menschliches  Allzumenschliches. 
NIETZSCHE.— Also  sprach  Zarathustra.     English  translation. 


374  BIBLIOGRAPHY. 

PATTEN  (Simon  N.).— The  Economic  Foundations  of  Pro- 
tection. 

PAULHAN.—L' Activitd  mentale  et  les  Elements  de  1'esprit. 

PAULHAN. — Les  Caracteres,  Les  Types  intellectuels,  Esprits 
logiques  et  esprits  faux.  Paris,  Alcan,  1896. 

PAYOT.— L'Education  de  la  volonte.  Paris,  Alcan,  1901,  i2th 
edition. 

PlLLON.— Annee  philosophique,  1868. 

PROAL. — Le  crime  et  la  peine.     Paris,  Alcan,  1891. 

RENARD. — Le  re'gime  socialiste.     Paris,  Alcan,  1898. 

RENOUVIER. — La  science  de  la  morale.     Paris,  Ladrange,  1869. 

RlBOT. — Psychology  of  the  Emotions  (Contemporary  Science 
Series),  Maladies  de  la  volonte,  Psychologic  de  1'attention, 
L'imagination  creatrice.  Paris,  Alcan. 

RICHARD. — Revue  critique,  "Revue  Philosophique,"  1896, 
t.  xlii.  p.  529. 

RICHARD. — "Revue  Philosophique,"  1899,  t.  xliii.  p.  476. 

ROMANES. — Mental  Evolution  in  Man. 

SABATIER. — Esquisse  d'une  philosophic  de  la  religion.  Fisch- 
bacher,  Paris,  6th  ed.,  1901. 

SEE  (H.). — Les  Classes  rurales  en  France  au  moyen  age. 
Paris,  Giard  et  Briere,  1901. 

SOLLIER  (Dr.). — Psychologic  de  1'idiot  et  de  Pimbecile.  Paris, 
Alcan,  1891. 

SPENCER. — Principles  of  Sociology.     London,  1870. 

SPENCER.— The  Data  of  Ethics.  Summary  of  Spencer's  Philo- 
sophy, by  Howard  Collins. 

SPINOZA.— Ethica.     Edit.  Van  Vloten  (English  trans.). 

STEIN. — La  Question  sociale  au  point  de  vue  philosophique. 
Paris,  Alcan,  1900. 

STIRNER. — Der  Einzige  und  sein  Eigenthum.  (French  trans. 
"  Revue  blanche,"  1900.) 

TANON. — L'£ volution  du  droit.     Alcan,  1900. 

TARDE. —  Les  lois  de  1'imitation.  2nd  ed.  "La  logique 
sociale."  Paris,  Alcan,  1895. 

TOLSTOI.— What's  to  be  Done?— Pamphilius  and  Julius— Com- 
mentary on  the  Gospel,  etc. 

WHITE. — History  of  the  Conflict  between  Science  and  Religion. 

ZENKER.  —  Naturliche  Entwickelungsgeschichte  Gesellschaft. 
Berlin,  Reimer,  1899. 


INDEX. 


ABOUI.IA,  §33,  178 

Accident,  criminal  by,  §  75 

Action  :  —moral,  §  28,  pp.  53  et 
seq.',  voluntary,  do.,  first  stage 
of,  61,  62;  instinctive,  97;  im- 
moral, V.  ;  social,  in  dealing 
with  criminals,  350 

Acts  :  —  voluntary,  63  ;  moral, 
place  of  joy  in,  §  70  ;  immoral, 
V.  ;  why  called  vicious,  153 

Adams  (Brooks),  210;  (Maurice), 
236;;. 

Esthetics,  §  59,  §  69 

Agent,  61,  §47,  93 

Agriculture  (and  property),  224 

Alcoholism,  §  86 

Althusius,  276,  281 

Altruism,  §61,  134,  144,  233,  235, 
270 

Ambil  Anak,  196,  199 

Amor  Dei  intellectualis,  117  et 
seq.. 

Andaman  Islanders,  169;?. 

Animal  societies,  128;  love  in,  129 

Animals,  man  and,  327 

Anomia,  and  crime,  187 

Antagonistic  reductives,  125,  133, 
140,  177 

Antecedent,  and  cause,  90 

Apaches,  199,  201 

Appreciation,  errors  of,  337 

Aptitudes,  273 

Aquinas,  St.  Thomas,  275 

Aristocracy,  §  122  ;  of  Plato,  42 

Aristotle,  3,  4,  30,  §23,  53,  70, 
114,  120,  138,  191,  205,  251, 

327 

Arts  and  ethics,  §  15  ;  of  human 
conduct,  26  et  seq.;  aim  of,  123 


Asceticism,  120 

Assaults,  indecent,  165,  174,  338 
Association,  §30,  219 
Attention,  §30;    multilinear,  69; 
voluntary,    139 ;    pathology   of, 

175 
Austin^     25711.,     259;*. ,     260;;., 

267;*.,  2747;.,  275;/.,  276;;. 
Authority,  205 

Bachofen,  145,  196 

Bain,  98;; 

Baldwin,  326 

B  alii  on,  204 

Bancroft,  200 

Beautiful,  cult  of,  §  69 

Bedouins,  201 

Belief,  11 

Belot,  8 

Bent  ham,  103 

Bergsen,  63,  85/2. 

Bernard  (Claude),  82,  83 

Birds,  monogamtc,  196 

Blackmail,  167 

Bo  din,  275 

Bon  (le],  158 

Bonald  (de),  278 

Bonconr,  219,  221,  222//.,  287 

Bolocodos,  20 1 

Bou°le,  207,  209 

Bourret  (Cardinal),  9 

Boutroux,  i6«. 

Brentano,  219 

Brunschvicg,  148,  150;;. 

Burchardt,  200 

Burke,  277 

CAPITAL,  §  107,  227 
Cartesian  ism,  $\n. 


376 


INDEX. 


Caste,  205 

Cause  (and  antecedent),  90 

Centralisation,  pp.  284  et  seq. 

Chabot,  146 

Chamberlain,  126;;.,  134^.,  140/7., 
1 5O;/. 

Character,  origin  of,  §  44 ;  pos- 
sible modification  of,  346 

Charity,  266 

Children,  organising  power,  134  ; 
primitive  condition  of,  200 ; 
work  of,  308 ;  duties  towards, 
321  ;  their  duties,  324 

Choice,  54 ;  of  the  best,  70 ;  in- 
telligible, 93 

Christianity,  3 ;  sociological  ex- 
planation of  its  spread,  9,  208 

Chrysippus,  127 

Clan,  and  property,  224 

Classes  (the),  205 

Cleanthes,  1 8,  120,  123 

Clergy,  hostility  to  evolutionism,  7 

Collective  sentiments,  §  108,  228 

Collins,  232;*.,  233;*. 

Comennts,  320 

Communism,  225 

Competition,  292 

Comte,  116,  191,  194,  232 

Conception,  54,  §29,  143 

Conduct,  rational,  §  19,  35  ;  sys- 
tematic, 36,  153;  instinctive, 
54  ;  reprehensible,  155 

Conflict,  necessary,  §  119 

Conscience,    33,    §  45 ;    voice    of, 

75 

Conscious  processes,  §  35 
Consciousness,  moral,  §  17  ;  of  the 

good,  33 
Constraint,  264 
Contract,  §  100 
Co-education,  320 
Co-operation,  306 
Corporations,    suppression   of 

ancient,  227 

Corvee,  and  the  State,  297 
Cosmology,  7 
Coste,  209,  210,  216,  285 
Coulanges  (Fustel  de),  207 
Cratyhis,  \\$n. 
Crime,    §  72  ;    due   to    unsatisfied 

needs,  172 


Criminal,   §73;     classes  of,   §74, 

§  84  ;  insane,  §  76. 
Criminologists,  156  et  seq. 
Crisis,  the  moral,  I 
Criticism,    spirit  of,    I  ;    right  of, 

13  ;  abstention  from,  246 
Ciillh-e,  ITS'1- 

Culture,  and  inheritance,  273/2. 
Customs,  ancient,  preserved,  156 

DaUemagne,  172 

Dareste,  304 

Dai-gun,  21 5«. 

Darin,  22,  241 

Darwin,  15,  236 

Daivson,  198 

Degenerates,  intelligent,  §  78 

Degeneration,  185 

Delbos,  34//. 

Deliberation,    54,    §34,    67,    143, 

340 

Descartes,  23 
Desire,  §  54 
Despotism,  §  120 
Determinism,  72  et  seq.,  §43,   185 

et  seq.;  of  immoral  actions,  V  , 

pp.  152  et  seq. 
Devotion,  122,  §  128,  262 
D'fadst,  9 
Dieyeries,  197 
Diogenes  Laertius,  IOI,  121 
Disaggregation,  mental,  177 
Disintegration,  social,  3 
Dissociation,  57 
Disturbance,  social,  §  86 
Divorce,  321 

Dugas,  14,  44,  45,  137;;.,  327 
Dutkheivi,    8,     16,     17,    18,    74, 

109;*.,     now.,    187,    195,    204, 

206,  218,  231,  287 
Duty,    14,    15,  26  et  seq.,  36,  44, 

75,  76,  266,  282 

ECONOMIC,  life,  193 ;  primitive 
state,  §  loi  ;  evolution,  §  102, 
294  ;  facts,  order  of,  294 

Economy,  political,  and  morality, 
296 

Edgeworth,  tfn. 

Education,  duty  of  State,  §  140 ; 
and  sanction,  352 


INDEX. 


377 


Ego,  origin  of,  82,  93 
Egoism,  §  55,  128 
Egyptians,  207 
Ellis   (Havelock), 


i8i«.,  240;;. 

Emotion,  shocks,  136 

Encyclopedia  Britannica,  41^., 
275«. 

Endogamy,  192,  195,  197 

Enthusiasm,  close  of  era  of,  10 

Environment,  186 

Epicureanism,  4,  5,  101 

Epicurus,  84,  95,  101,  102,  103, 
1  20,  150,  327 

Equality,  §  96 

Eroticism,  116 

Espinas,  128,  203 

Ethics,  and  metaphysics,  5  ;  and 
religion,  §5;  and  science,  n, 
§  10;  and  arts,  §  15;  indepen- 
dent, §  7  ;  science  of,  13  ;  Kan- 
tian, §  9  ;  technical  character 
of,  §  12;  social,  §  16;  compared 
to  mathematics,  13  ;  pure  and 
applied,  40;  of  mind  and  nature, 
23  ;  individual  and  social,  III. 

Ethical,  religion,  10;  research, 
40,  48 

Evolution,  hostility  of  clergy  to, 
7  ;  and  Spencer,  46  ;  obedience 
to  law  of  duty,  47  ;  of  law  and 
morals,  194;  family,  §89;  politi- 
cal, §  99  ;  economic,  §  102  ;  of 
social  sentiments,  233  ;  socio- 
logical, §112;  social,  254;  in- 
dividual, 262  ;  conscious,  265 

Exaggeration,  §  82,  177 

Exercise,  §  71 

Exhibitionist  mania,  174 

Exogamy,  192,  195,  197 

Expansion,  force  of  vital,  pp.  126 
et  seq. 

FAMILY,    74  ;   dissolution,   §   92  ; 

future  of,  §  93 
Fanaticism,  228 
Fault,  152  et  seq. 
Fear,    138;   a  normal  sentiment? 

363 

Fecundity,  128 


Fere,  I4O«.,  i68;/. 

Ferrer -o,  315 

Ferri,  157,  158,  159,  160,  366 

Ferrus,  157 

Firmness,  135,  §66 

Fouillee,  6,  9,  ion.,  130;*. ,  236;*., 

248,  249;*.,  282 
Fragapane,  212 
France  (A. ),  360 
Eraser,  198 
Fraternity,  326 
Freedom,  208 
Frtgier,  157,  159 
Friendship,  326 

Gaillon,  177,  179 

Gall,  157 

Galton,  155 

Games,  128 

Garafolo,  158 

Generosity,  §63,  127,  265 

Gide,  244 

Goblot,  1 86 

Good,  the,   70;   the  idea  of,  and 

the  tendency  to,  §  38 ;  and  the 

beautiful,  §  69 
Government,  208,  §  97,  274 
Grassier,  140^. 
Greece,  3 
Gregory  VII.,  275 
Grosse,  197,  215 
Grotius,  276,  281 
Gttibert,  9 
Gtiyau,    2$n.,     31,    73^.,    77«., 

ioiw.,   I04«.,  124,   124^.,  128, 

129,    130^.,    146,    150,     162;?., 

163;*.,  175;;.,  248 
Guyot,  219 


HAPPINESS,  greatest  of  greatest 
number,  104  ;  intellectual,  §  57  ; 
§  70  ;  result  of  moral  action,  355 

Harris  (T.  L.),  241 

Hedonism,  §  51 

Hegel,  145,  278,  282 

Heredity,  59,  75,  §  86 

Hereditary  property,  §  133 

Historical  school,  282 

Hobbes,  250,  276,  278,  281,  282 

Hoffbauer,  i68w. 


378 


INDEX. 


Holland,  274/7.,  276;;. 

Hottze,  182 

Hughes \  162 

Hugo,  277 

Humanity,  love  of,  117;  religion 

of,  §  1 1 1 
Hunger,  193 
Huret,  157 
Hypocrisy,  330 

IDEA,  directing,  of  organism,  82 
Ideal,  and  real,  §  II  ;  moral,  25  ; 
psychological,   §  66,  45,    51   et 
seq.;  construction  of,  49 
Idealism,  §  13,  22,  283 
Idealists,  21 

Idee-force,  86,  93/7.,  174  et  seq. 
Idiot,  morality  of,  163 
Imagination,  §  29 
Imbecile,  morality  of,  163 
Imitation,   73;  and  sympathy,  368 
Immorality,  cause  of,   155  ;  nature 
of,   292 ;    struggle  against,    IV. 

P-  334 

Imperatives,  of  Kant,  26  et  seq. 
Impressions,    communicability   of, 

124  _ 
Impulsive,    criminal,     157,     347  ; 

man,  348 
Immutability,  348 
Individual,   dignity  of  (v.   Kant), 

§21;  the  moral,  127,  135  et  seq. 
Individualism,  227,  §  113,  284 
Industrialism,  §  107 
Inheritance,  and  culture,  273;?. 
Instinct,  gregarious,  74 
Intentions,  moral,  324 
Interest,  §  54;  and  desire,    105; 

collective,  §  56 
Invention,  24,  25,  39,  283 
Instability,      pathological,      176 ; 

mental,  177  ;  and  aboulia,  §  33 
Instruction,  obligatory,  p.  290 
Irreflection,  §  36 
Irresponsibility,  343 
James,    W.,   57,    58,    67,     15011., 

I75».,  176 
Janet  (Paul),  37,  137,  175/7.,  354; 

(Pierre)  177/7. 
Jay,  221 
Jems,  255 


Jones,  198 
Joy,  §  70 

Judge,  the  State  as,  291 
Jus,  vitse  et  necis,  201 ;   maritale, 
203  ;  utendi,  216  ;  abutendi,  216 
Justice,  42,  204,  250,  §  128,  §  129 

Kant,  his  philosophy,  14 ;  his 
Ethics,  §  9  ;  Critique  of  Pure 
Reason,  15;  his  imperatives,  26 
et  seq.\  and  the  future  of  hu- 
manity, 29 ;  and  the  dignity  of 
the  human  person,  31,  34,  36, 
39,  §126;  on  the  formal  con- 
ditions of  morality,  34 ;  on  ab- 
solute moral  value,  37 ;  his 
method,  §  22,  40 ;  and  pure 
reason,  52 ;  on  the  unique 
motive  of  moral  conduct,  64,  81 ; 
and  Free  Will,  §  43  ;  his  theory 
applies  to  superhuman  beings, 
65 ;  his  psychology,  78 ;  his 
hypothesis,  82;  his  aesthetics, 
123,  124,  143,  145;  and  pro- 
perty, §  130;  and  personal  value, 
274 ;  on  social  contract,  277 ; 
and  popular  will,  280;  on  dele- 

fation    of    the   powers    of    the 
tate,   281  ;    and  responsibility, 
335  ;  and  sanction,  354 
Kovalewsky,  225,  242/7. 
Krause,  200 

Kropotkin  (Prince),  203/2.,  204/7., 
264/7. 

LABOUR,  division  of,  §  103  ;  §  107 ; 

defined,  309 
Laccassagne,  158,  349 
Lalande,  196,  202,  207 
Land,  224 
Lang,  228/7. 
Lav e ley e,  224 
Law,  204,  §  99 
Lecky,  98/2. 
Legislation,  §  134 
Legrain,  163,  182 
Leibnitz,  41,  133,  145 
Lerminier,  279 
Letourneau,  192/7.,  196/7.,  228/7., 

303 

Leviathan  ( Hobbes),  248,  282 


INDEX. 


379 


Levirate,  195,  198  et  seq. 

Liberty,  the  ratio  essendi  of  duty, 
:5>  33>  noumenal,  33;  and 
morality,  II.  pp.  80  et  set/.,  §  45, 
§  46 ;  individual,  235  ;  meta- 
physical, §  126 

Lichtenberger,  236,  239«. 

Life,  law  of,  46  ;  political,  §95 

Locke,  277,  281 

Lombrcso,  140;*.,  156,  158,  160, 
i62w.,  i68«.,  I79«.,  i8iw.,  182, 

184,  315 
Lonrbet,  315 
Louvie,  244 

Love,  116,  129,  193,  242,  243 
Lynching,  352 

MACHINERY.  218,  227 
Mackenzie  (J.  S.),  41/2.,  43«.,  64;;., 

98«.,       II2«  ,       207;;.,        209«., 
2I9«.,       222/7  ,      227//,       233/7., 

263;;.,  273«. 

Mackenzie,  198 

MacLennan,  195 

Magnan,  164,  182 

Maine  (Sir  H.),  196,  207/7.,  21  iw., 
213/7.,  222/7.,  267/7. 

Malapert,  2<)  et  seq. 

Malebranche,  37,  342 

Man,  a  psychological  being,  10 ; 
a  social  being,  10 ;  makes  his 
own  morality,  1 1  ;  the  divine  in, 
114;  the  wise,  121  et  seq.  ;  and 
animals,  327 

Mania,  "reasoning,"  162;  "ex- 
hibitionist," 174 

Manneis,  good,  §  36 

Manouvrier,  182 

Marion,  35 

Marriage,  186,  214,  317 

Marro,  196 

Marshall,  217/7.,  227/7. 

Marx  (Karl),  6,  226/7.    227;;.,  304 

Matriarchate,  195,  §90 

Mazzarella,  195/7.,  196,  200 

Matidsley,  157,  158,  162/7.,  163;;., 
1 69;*.,  179;;. 

Mean,  the  golden,  43,  138 

Meek,  the,  §  121 

Megalomania,  165 

Meno,  70/7. 


Merder,  ioo;/. ,  126;;.,  140;*. 

Merit,  358 

Merriani,  278 

Metaphysics,  5,  50 

Method,  §  26 

Middendorf  ( von ),  2Oo;/ . 

Middle  Ages,  the,  and  friendship, 

327 

Might,  250 
Mill  (John    Stuart),    36,    46,    47, 

IOOW.,   IO7W.,   112 

Mobiles  et  Motifs,  distinguished, 
87«. 

Moderation,  §  67 

Modesty,  332 

Mohammed,  10,  255 

Monadistic  and  Monistic  views  of 
justice,  263^. 

Money,  210,  243 

Moral,  crisis,  §  I  ;  Philosophy,  5  ; 
Ideal,  7;  and  physical  laws,  19; 
theory,  25 ;  activity,  25,  40 ; 
hygiene,  28  ;  consciousness,  §17  ; 
sense,  32 ;  Will,  I.  :  worth  and 
duty,  §  20  ;  subjectivism,  §  39 ; 
inertia,  103  ;  apotheosis  of,  105  ; 
precepts,  105;  individual,  134; 
firmness,  135;  virtues,  142;  in- 
sanity, 162  ;  imbecility,  162 ; 
vertigo,  179;  suggestion,  367 

Moralists,  Scotch  and  French,  32 

Morality,  ancient,  §  2 ;  as  taught 
by  philosophers,  5 ;  conditions 
of,  §  6  ;  scientific,  16  ;  its  do- 
main, 19  ;  technical  character, 
§12;  and  evolution,  20;  and 
the  "imperative,"  26  et  seq.; 
applied,  40;  sociological,  "of 
dry  bread,"  101 ;  mystical,  Il6; 
Greek,  144  ;  in  economics,  292  ; 
"of  slaves,"  363 

Morgan  (Lloyd),  125;;. 

Morselli,  157,  169;*.,  187/7. 

Munroe,  320 

Mysticism,  §  58 

Napoleon,  254 
Naturalism,  §  13,  §  50,  283 
Nature  of  man,  121 
Neo-platonists,  115 
Nieboer,  198,  222 


3'8o 


INDEX. 


Nietzsche,  236  et  seq. 
Non-resistance,  241,  §  118 
Nounienon,  33,  81 

OBLIGATION,  moral,  44,  75,  204 
Obsession,  §81,  174 
Oceania,  199 
Ontogeny  of  societies,  191 
Ojibeway  Indians,  198 
Optimism,  Stoic,  122 
Organisation,    social,    §  65 ;    eco- 
nomic, 292 
Orthodoxy,  289 
Over-man,  the,  §  114 
Overwork,  1 86 
Ovid,  6gn. 

PAIN-PLEASURE,  1137;..,  125 

Passions,  118 

Pastoral  tribes,  215 

Patten,  293 

Paulhan,  57 

Perception.  §29,  §31 

Perfection,  animal,  96 ;  intel- 
lectual, 114 

Person,  the  real  agent,  §47 

Phaedo,  23;*,  42;*. 

Phaedrtis,  \\$n. 

Philosophy,  "  poverty  of,"  6 ; 
powerlessness  of,  6 ;  of  science, 
6;  rights  of,  12;  phenomenist, 
90 

Physiology,  mental,  45,  55 

Pig,  doctrine  of,  satisfied,  108 

Pillon,  31,  50 

Pity,  122,  239 

Plato,  3,  4,  22,  23,  30,  42,  1 20, 
205,  249,  298 

Play,  128 

Pleasure,  psychological,  136;  in- 
tellectual, 245,  §  70 

Pleasure-Pain,  11377..,  125 

Plotinus,  115 

Plutocracy,  §  98 

Polyandry,  195 

Polygamy,  195 

Population,  206,  208 

Positivism,  116 

Potestas,  patria,  §  92 

Powerlessness,  of  religion,  8 ;  of 
philosophy,  6 


Prevision,     sociological,    20,    25 ; 

scientific,  20 
Prichard,  162 
Priestly,  104 
Proal,  20977.,  21  in. 
Promiscuity,  192,  195 
Property,  202,  §  10$,  §  106,  §  130, 

§131,  §132 
Prostitution,  315 
Proudhon,  279,  280 
Psychic,  nature  of  processes,  64 
Psychology,     scientific,     12 ;      its 

teaching,  53 
Puchta,  200 
Punishment,   immorality  of,   360 ; 

utilitarian  role  of,  361 
Pyromania,  169;;. 
Pyrrhonism,  4 

Qttetelet,  157 

Ratzel,  197 

Raymond,  176 

Real,  and  Ideal,  §  II 

Reason,  §  41  ;  data  of,  §  18 ;  de- 
fined by  Marion,  35 ;  pure 
practical,  §  27 ;  human  and 
animal,  96 

Recidivism,  159 

Reform,  §  132 

Religion,  3  ;  powerlessness  of,  8  ; 
of  Humanity  and  the  Unknow- 
able, §  in  ;  of  suffering,  240 

Religious  institutions,  192  ;  senti- 
ments, 332 

Renard,  298 

Renouvier,  13,  14,  16,  17,  31,  41, 
65,  86,  88,  io7«,  i2i«,  180, 
270,  314,  318,  321 

Renunciation,  242 

Republic  (of  Plato),  42;;.,  359 

Respect  of  children  to  parents,  326 

Responsibility,  social,  334 

Revolt,  right  to,  284 

Ribot,  5577..,  69,  loow.,  116,  12477. , 
125;;.,  12777..,  140;;.,  15077,., 
162;;.,  i68«. ,  16977.,  17577. 

Richard,  315,  363 

Right,  204,  250,  §123,  §124, 
§  125,  §  126,  §  127,  §  130 

"  Rights  of  Man,"  268 


INDEX. 


Risk,  §71 
Ritchie ,  239;;. 
Robertson,  275*1.,  277/7. 
Rochefoucauld  (de  La),  126 
Rogers,  Thorold,  226/1. 
Romanes,  56,  97 
Romanticism,  40 
Rousseau,  33,  277,  278,  280,  281 
Ruskin,  12311. 

Sabatier,  289 

Samoyedes,  201 

Sanction,  352 

Savage,  162 

Savigny,  277 

Science,  of  Ethics,  16  ;  a  product 
of  social  life,  38 ;  conscience, 
liberty  and,  §  45 ;  instruction 
should  be  given  to  all,  290 

Schelling,  278 

Schiller,  193^. 

Schmidt,  249 

Schutz,  197 

See,  22611. 

Self- perception,  §  32 

Semitic  tribes,  207 

Sensorial  type,  §  31 

Sentiments,  collective,  §  108 ; 
primitive,  §  109;  genuine  human, 

330 

Sergi,  157,  158 

Sexes,  co-education  and  equality 
of,  320 

Sexual  love,  126,  129;  instinct 
morbid,  165,  181  ;  disorders, 
i6gn. ;  relations,  192,  196 

Sidgwick,  64;*.,  II5«.,  138;;. 

Sioux,  199 

Sisuwndi.,  280 

Slavery,  193,  197,  199  et  seq., 
§  105,  251,  276 

Smith,  Adam,  §  24 

Sociability,  39,  76,  126.  §64,  141 

Social  contract,  §137;  disintegra- 
tion, 3  ;  conscience,  39  ;  statics 
and  dynamics,  191  ;  responsi- 
bility, 334;  action,  350 

Societies,  animal,  128,  203,  §94; 
organisation,  §65,  133 

Sociology,  its  role,  17;  interpreta- 
tion of  its  data,  21;  present 


state    of,    §  87 ;     anticipations, 
§  112 
Socrates,  70,   108,    154,    156,  254, 

337 

Sohm,  200 

Solidarity,  122;  immoral  effects 
of,  §  85  ;  professional,  221,  235, 
273;  Durkheim's  "mechanical." 
74,  204,  231;  "organic,"  218, 
231  ;  in  economic  order,  301 

Sollier,  163 

Sorley,  98;*.,  124^.,  207 n. 

Soul,  phenomena  of,  23 ;  of  divine 
origin,  42 

Sovereignty,  §  135,  §  137 

Spencer,  Herbert,  8,  §25,  53,  125, 
128,  146,  193;?.,  195,  224,  225, 
230  et  seq.,  267 n.,  284 

Spinoza,  38,  41,  52,  53,  89,  112, 
§59,239,  250,251 

Spiritualism,  §  13  ;  dualistic,  7,  23 

Stability,  morbid,  176 

State,  202  et  seq.,  V. 

Stein,  285 

Steinmetz,  200 

Stirner,  249 

Stoicism,  3,  4,  18,  §60,  138,  208, 

327,  385 

Stout,  55«.,  iijn. 
Strttelens,  182 
Subjectivity,  its  role,  26 
Suggestion,       pathological,       n  ; 

moral,  367 
Suicide,  187 
Sympathy,  and  duty,  44  ;  mark  of 

aptitude,    73,    74,     124,    §61, 

231 ;  imitation,  368 

TABOO,  228 

Tacitus,  224 

Tanon,  212 

Tarde,  73,  146,  284,  288 

Taxation,  300 

Temperance,  139 

Tendencies,  instinctive,  53  et  seq.', 
fugitive,  62 ;  causes  of  volition, 
80;  conflict  of,  71;  to  good, 
§38;  and  heredity,  §40;  indi- 
vidual and  collective,  76 ;  differ- 
ent moral,  §  49 ;  to  pleasure, 
99  et  seq.,  192;  modified,  106  ; 


382 


INDEX. 


to  happiness,  113;  attracted  by 
mystery,  116;  social,  124  et 
seq.,  §65;  constituting  char- 
acter, 136  et  seq.',  to  co-ordinate, 
152  et  seq. ;  to  crime,  "V.*  passim  ; 
of  strong  to  oppress  the  weak, 
223 ;  development  of  scientific 
and  artistic,  229  et  seq.  ;  aristo- 
cratic and  democratic,  252 

7'imteus,  23,  42;;. 

Tolstoi,  236  et  seq.,  §  Il6 

Totem,  228 

Tourniac,  16572. 

Tradition,  power  of,  74 

Truth,  §  140 

Tyranny,  socialistic,  220 

UKBERMENSCH,  §  114 
Unbalanced,  criminals,  §  79 
Unions,  trades,  218,  §  104,  §  139 
Unity,  religious 
Unfit,  sacrifice  of,  §  115 
Uniformity,     of     tendencies     and 

heredity,  §  40 
Unknowable,  the,  §  ill 
Utilitarianism,  49,  103,  106  et  seq. 

VENGEANCE,  212 
Verga,  162 


Verne  (Jules),  179 
Vertigo,  moral,  §83 
Vice,  153 
Vidocq,  157 
Violence,  245 
Virtue,  private,  37 ;  and  sentiment, 

44 ;  and  truth,  §  68 
Voisi,  164 

WAGES  system,  304 

Walker,  217/1. 

Warnots,  183 

Wealth,  and  morality,  295 

Westermarck,  193^. 

White,  Sn. 

Wife,  choice  of,  186 

Will,  good,  79 

Woman,    §90;     work    of,     308; 

rights  of,  314 
Work,    of    women   and   children, 

308 
Workman,  the,  his  value,  309 

Yvernes,  158 

Zarathrustra,  237  et  seq. 
Zenker,  211,  225,  249;*. 
Zeno,  123 


THE  WALTER   SCOTT  PUBLISHING   CO.,    LTD.,    NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


DRAMATIC    ESSAYS 

(3  VOLS.). 

EJited  by  WILLIAM  ARCHER  and  ROBERT  W.  LOWE. 

Crown  8vo,  Cloth,  Price  33.  6d.  each. 

VOL.  I. 

DRAMATIC  ESSAYS  BY  LEIGH  HUNT. 

Selected  and  Edited,  with  Notes  and  Introduction,  by  WILLIAM 
ARCHER  and  ROBERT  W.  LOWE.  With  an  Engraved  Portrait  of 
Leigh  Hunt  as  Frontispiece. 

This  Volume  contains  the  Criticisms  collected  by  LEIGH  HUNT 
himself  in  1807  (long  out  of  print),  and  the  admirable  articles  whicu 
he  contributed  more  than  twenty  years  later  to  "  The  Tatler,"  and 
never  republished. 

"All  students  of  drama  and  lovers  of  'the  play'  will  welcome  the 
admirably  produced  volume  of  Dramatic  Essays  by  Leigh  Hunt, 
selected  and  edited  by  Mr.  Archer  and  Mr.  Lowe,  with  notes,  and 
an  extremely  interesting  introduction  written  by  Mr.  Archer."— The 
World. 


VOL.   II. 

SELECTIONS    FROM    THE    CRITICISMS 

OF  WILLIAM  HAZLITT.  Annotated,  with  an  Introduction 
by  WILLIAM  ARCHER,  and  an  Engraved  Portrait  of  Hazlitt  as 
Frontispiece. 

"A  book  which  every  one  interested  in  the  history  of  the  London 
staire  will  prize  highly,  and  will  not  only  read  with  pleasure,  but  will 
desire  to  have  always  by  them  for  purposes  of  reference."— Scotsman, 


VOL.   III. 

SELECTIONS  FROM  THE  DRAMATIC 

CRITICISMS  (hitherto  uncollected)  OF  JOHN  FORSTER 
and  GEORGE  HENRY  LEWES.  With  Notes  and  an  Intro- 
duction by  WILLIAM  ARCHER  and  ROBERT  W.  LOWE,  and  a 
Portrait  of  George  Henry  Lewes  as  Frontispiece. 

"  The  volume,  which  is  carefully  edited,  contains  a  quantity  of  vivid 
portraiture,  and  will  be  welcomed  by  students  as  bringing  us  in  touch 
with  the  stage  of  the  early  fifties." — Literary  World, 


THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LIMITED. 
LONDON  AND  NEWCASTLE-ON-TVNE. 


BOOKS    OF    FAIRY    TALES. 

Crown  Svv,  Cloth  Elegant,  Price  3/6  per  Vol. 

ENGLISH    FAIRY   AND    OTHER 
FOLK  TALES. 

Selected  and  Edited,  with  an  Introduction, 

BY  EDWIN  SIDNEY  HARTLAND. 
With  Twelve  Full-Page  Illustrations  by  CHARLES  E.  BROCK. 


SCOTTISH  FAIRY  AND  FOLK  TALES. 

Selected  and  Edited,  with  an  Introduction, 

BY  SIR  GEORGE  DOUGLAS,  BART. 
With  Twelve  Full-Page  Illustration*  by  JAMES  TORRANCE 


IRISH  FAIRY  AND  FOLK  TALES. 

Selected  and  Edited,  with  an  Introduction, 

BY  W.  B.  YEATS. 
With  Twelve  Full-Page  Illustrations  by  JAMES  TORRANCE. 

THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LIMITED. 
LONDON  AND  NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


The  Contemporary  Science  Series. 

Edited  by  Havelock  Ellis. 


(i) 

THE  EVOLUTION  OF  SEX.  By  Profs.  PATRICK  GEDDES 
and  J.  A.  THOMSON.  With  92  Illustrations.  Fourth  and  Revised 
Edition.  6s. 

"  The  authors  have  brought  to  the  task—  as  indeed  their  names  guarantee—  a  wealth 
of  knowledge,  a  lucid  and  attractive  method  of  treatment,  and  a  rich  vein  of  pictur- 
esque language."  —  Nature. 

(2) 

ELECTRICITY     IN     MODERN     LIFE.       By    G.    W.    DE 

TUNZELMANN.     With  over  100  Illustrations.     33.  6d. 

"  A  clearly-written  and  connected  sketch  of  what  is  known  about  electricity  and 
magnetism,  the  more  prominent  modern  applications,  and  the  principles  on  which 
they  are  based."  —  Saturday  Review. 

(3) 

THE  ORIGIN  OF  THE  ARYANS,  BY  Dr.  ISAAC  TAYLOR. 
Illustrated.  Second  Edition,  35.  6d. 

"Canon  Taylor  is  probably  the  most  encyclopaedic  nil-round  scholar.  .  .  . 
His  volume  on  the  Origin  of  the  Aryans  is  a  first-rate  example  of  the  excellent 
account  to  which  he  can  turn  his  exceptionally  wide  and  varied  information.  .  .  . 
Masterly  and  exhaustive."—  Pall  Mall  Gazette. 

(4) 

PHYSIOGNOMY  AND  EXPRESSION.  By  P.  MANTE- 
GAZZA.  Illustrated.  Second  Edition.  35.  6d. 

"  Brings  this  highly  interesting  subject  even  with  the  latest  researches.  .  .  . 
Professor  Mantegazza  is  a  writer  full  of  life  and  spirit,  and  the  natural  attractiveness 
of  his  subject  is  not  destroyed  by  his  scientific  handling  of  it."—  Literary  World  (Boston). 


EVOLUTION  AND  DISEASE.     By  J.  B.  SUTTON,  F.R.C.S. 
With  135  Illustrations.     33.  6d. 

"  The  book  is  as  interesting  as  a  novel,  without  sacrifice  of  accuracy  or  system,  and 
is  calculated  to  give  an  appreciation  of  the  fundamentals  of  pathology  to  the  lay 
reader,  while  forming  a  useful  collection  of  illustrations  of  disease  for  medical 
reference."—  Journal  of  Mental  Science. 


(6) 

THE  VILLAGE  COMMUNITY.      By  G.  L.  GOMME.     Illus- 
trated.    35.  6d. 

"  His  book  will  probably  remain  for  some  time  the  best  work  of  reference  for  facts 
bearing  on  those  traces  of  the  village  community  which  have  not  been  effaced  by 
conquest,  encroachment,  and  the  heavy  hand  of  Roman  law."— Scottish  Leader. 

(7) 

THE  CRIMINAL.     By  HAVELOCK  ELLIS.     Illustrated.     Third 
Edition,  Revised  and  Enlarged,    6s. 

"The  sociologist,  the  philosopher,  the  philanthropist,  the  novelist— all,  indeed, 
for  whom  the  study  of  human  nature  has  any  attraction— will  find  Mr.  Ellis  full  of 
interest  and  suggestiveness."— Academy. 

(8) 

SANITY   AND    INSANITY.       By    Dr.    CHARLES    MERCIER. 
Illustrated.     33.  6d. 

"Taken  as  a  whole,  it  is  the  brightest  book  on  the  physical  side  of  mental  science 
published  in  our  time."— Pall  Mall  Gazette. 

(9) 

HYPNOTISM.     By    Dr.    ALBERT   MOLL.      Fifth   Edition,    Re- 
vised and  Enlarged,    35.  6d. 

"Marks  a  step  of  some  importance  in  the  study  of  some  difficult  physiological  and 
psychological  problems  which  have  not  yet  received  much  attention  in  the  scientific 
world  of  England."— Nature. 

(10) 

MANUAL  TRAINING.    By  Dr.  C.  M.  WOODWARD,  Director 
of  the  Manual  Training  School,  St.  Louis.     Illustrated.     35.  6d. 

"There  is  no  greater  authority  on  the  subject  than  Professor  Woodward." 
—Manchester  Guardian. 

(11) 

THE    SCIENCE    OF     FAIRY    TALES.      By    E.     SIDNEY 
HARTLAND.     35.  6d. 

"Mr.  Hartland's  book  will  win  the  sympathy  of  all  earnest  students,  both  by  the 
knowledge  it  displays,  and  by  a  thorough  love  and  appreciation  of  his  subject,  which 
is  evident  throughout." — Spectator. 

(12) 
PRIMITIVE  FOLK.     By  ELIE  RECLUS.     3s.  6d. 

"  An  attractive  and  useful  introduction  to  the  study  of  some  aspects  of  ethnography." 
— Nature. 


(13) 

THE      EVOLUTION     OF     MARRIAGE.       By      Professor 
.  LETOURNEAU.     Second  Edition.     35.  6d. 

"Among  the  distinguished  French  students  of  sociology,  Professor  Letourneau  has 
long  stood  in  the  first  rank.  He  approaches  the  great  study  of  man  free  from  bias 
and  shy  of  generalisations.  To  collect,  scrutinise,  and  appraise  facts  is  his  chief 
business.  In  the  volume  before  us  he  shows  these  qualities  in  an  admirable  degree." 
—Science. 

(14) 

BACTERIA   AND   THEIR  PRODUCTS.      By  Dr.   G.  SIMS 
WOODHEAD.     Illustrated.     Third  Edition.     35.  6d. 

"  An  excellent  summary  of  the  present  state  of  knowledge  of  the  subject."— Lancet, 

(15) 
EDUCATION  AND  HEREDITY.     By  J.  M.  GUYAU.    3s.  6d. 

"It  is  at  once  a  treatise  on  sociology,  ethics,  and  psedagogics.  It  is  doubtful 
whether  among  all  the  ardent  evolutionists  who  have  had  their  say  on  the  moral 
and  the  educational  question  any  one  has  carried  forward  the  new  doctrine  so  boldly 
to  its  extreme  logical  consequence." — Professor  SULLY  in  Mind. 

(16) 

THE    MAN   OF  GENIUS.     By  Prof.  LOMBROSO.     Illustrated. 

3s.  6d. 

"  By  far  the  most  comprehensive  and  fascinating  collection  of  facts  and  generalisa- 
tions concerning  genius  which  has  yet  been  brought  together."— Journal  of  Mental 
Science. 

(17) 

THE    HISTORY    OF    THE    EUROPEAN    FAUNA.       By 

R.  F.  SCHARFF,  B.Sc.,  PH.D.,  F.Z.S.     6s. 

"The  book  is  trustworthy,  the  information  carefully  gathered  and  judiciously 
treated."—  The  Bookman. 

(18) 

PROPERTY:    ITS    ORIGIN   AND   DEVELOPMENT.     By 

CH.  LETOURNEAU,  General  Secretary  to  the  Anthropological  Society, 
Paris,  and  Professor  in  the  School  of  Anthropology,  Paris.     35.  6d. 

"  M.  Letourneau  has  read  a  great  deal,  and  he  seems  to  us  to  have  selected  and 
interpreted  his  facts  with  considerable  judgment  and  learning."— Westminster  Review. 

(19) 

VOLCANOES,   PAST  AND    PRESENT.     By  Prof.   EDWARD 

HULL,  LL.D.,  F.R.S.     33.  6d. 

"  A  very  readable  account  of  the  phenomena  of    volcanoes  and   earthquakes. 
— Nature. 


(20) 

PUBLIC  HEALTH.     By  Dr.  J.  F    J.  SYKES.    With  numerous 
Illustrations.    '35.  6d. 

"  Not  by  any  means  a  mere  compilation  or  a  dry  record  of  details  and  statistics, 
but  it  takes  up  essential  points  in  evolution,  environment,  prophylaxis,  and  sanitation 
bearing  upon  the  preservation  of  public  health."— 


(21) 

MODERN  METEOROLOGY.  AN  ACCOUNT  OF  THE 
GROWTH  AND  PRESENT  CONDITION  OF  SOME  BRANCHES  OF 
METEOROLOGICAL  SCIENCE.  By  FRANK  WALDO,  PH.D.,  Member 
of  the'  German  and  Austrian  Meteorological  Societies,  etc.  ;  late 
Junior  Professor,  Signal  Service,  U.S.A.  With  112  Illustrations. 
35.  6d. 

"  The  present  volume  is  the  best  on  the  subject  for  general  use  that  we  have  seen." 
—Daily  Telegraph  (London). 

(22) 

THE  GERM-PLASM :    A  THEORY  OF   HEREDITY.     By 

AUGUST   WEISMANN,    Professor    in    the    University    of  Freiburg-in- 
Breisgau.     With  24  Illustrations.     6s. 

"  There  has  been  no  work  published  since  Darwin's  own  books  which  has  so 
thoroughly  handled  the  matter  treated  by  him,  or  has  done  so  much  to  place  in  order 
and  clearness  the  immense  complexity  of  the  factors  of  heredity,  or,  lastly,  has 
brought  to  light  so  many  new  facts  and  considerations  bearing  on  the  subject."— 
British  Medical  Journal. 

(23) 

INDUSTRIES  OF  ANIMALS.  By  F.  HOUSSAY.  With 
numerous  Illustrations.  35.  6d. 

"  His  accuracy  is  undoubted,  yet  his  facts  out-marvel  all  romance.  These  facts  are 
here  made  use  of  as  materials  wherewith  to  form  the  mighty  fabric  of  evolution." 
—Manchester  Guardian. 

(24) 

MAN  AND  WOMAN.  By  HAVELOCK  ELLIS.  Illustrated. 
Second  Edition*  6s. 

"  Mr.  Havelock  Ellis  belongs,  in  some  measure,  to  the  continental  school  of  anthro- 
pologists; but  while  equally  methodical  in  the  collection  of  facts,  he  is  far  more 
cautious  in  the  invention  of  theories,  and  he  has  the  further  distinction  of  being  not 
only  able  to  think,  but  able  to  write.  His  book  is  a  sane  and  impartial  considera- 
tion, from  a  psychological  and  anthropological  point  of  view,  of  a  subject  which  is 
certainly  of  primary  interest."—  Athenaeum. 


(25) 

THE  EVOLUTION  OF  MODERN  CAPITALISM.  By 
JOHN  A.  HOBSON,  M.A.  Second  Edition.  35.  6d. 

"  Every  p'ige  affords  evidence  of  wide  and  minute  study,  a  weighing  of  facts  as 
conscientious  as  it  is  acute,  a  keen  sense  of  the  importance  of  certain  points  as  to 
which  economists  of  all  schools  have  hitherto  been  confused  and  careless,  and  an 
impartiality  generally  so  great  as  to  give  no  indication  of  his  [Mr.  Hobson's]  per- 
sonal sympathies."— Pali  Mall  Gazette. 

(26) 

APPARITIONS   AND  THOUGHT-TRANSFERENCE.     By 

FRANK  PODMORE,  M.A.     33.  6d. 

"A  very  sober  and  interesting  little  book.  .  .  .  That  thought-transference  is  a 
real  thing,  though  not  perhaps  a  very  common  thing,  he  certainly  shows."— Spectator. 

(27) 

AN  INTRODUCTIONTO  COMPARATIVE  PSYCHOLOGY. 

By  Professor  C.  LLOYD  MORGAN,  F.R.S.     With  Diagrams.     6s. 

"A  strong  and  complete  exposition  of  Psychology,  as  it  takes  shape  in  a  mind 
previously  informed  with  biological  science.  .  .  .  Well  written,  extremely  entertain- 
ing, and  intrinsically  valuable."— Saturday  Review. 

(28) 

THE  ORIGINS  OF  INVENTION :  A  STUDY  OF  INDUSTRY 
AMONG  PRIMITIVE  PEOPLES.  By  OTIS  T.  MASON,  Curator  of 
the  Department  of  Ethnology  in  the  United  States  National  Museum. 
35.  6d. 

"A  valuable  history  of  the  development  of  the  inventive  faculty."— Nature. 

(29) 

THE  GROWTH  OF  THE  BRAIN:  A  STUDY  OF  THE 
NERVOUS  SYSTEM  IN  RELATION  TO  EDUCATION.  By  HENRY 
HERBERT  DONALDSON,  Professor  of  Neurology  in  the  University  of 
Chicago.  33.  6d. 

"  We  can  say  with  confidence  that  Professor  Donaldson  has  executed  his  work 
with  much  care,  judgment,  and  discrimination."— The  Lancet. 

(30) 

EVOLUTION  IN  ART:  As  ILLUSTRATED  BY  THE  LIFE- 
HISTORIES  OF  DESIGNS.  By  Professor  ALFRED  C.  HADDON, 
F.R.S.  With  130  Illustrations.  6s. 

"It  is  impossible  to  speak  too  highly  of  this  most  unassuming  and  invaluable 
book."— Journal  Anthropological  Institute. 


(31) 

THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  THE  EMOTIONS.  By  TH. 
RIBOT,  Professor  at  the  College  of  France,  Editor  of  the  Revue 
Philosophique.  6s. 

"Charmingly  written,  and  full  of  lucid  explanation  and  brilliant  comparison.  A 
masterly  exposition." — British  Medical  Journal. 

(32) 

HALLUCINATIONS  AND    ILLUSIONS:   A  STUDY  OF  THE 

FALLACIES  OF  PERCEPTION.     By  EDMUND  PARISH.     6s. 
"  The  most  comprehensive  and  most  scientific  work  on  false  perception  that  has  up 
till  now  been  written  in  any  language  " — Journal  of  Mental  Science. 

(33) 
THE  NEW  PSYCHOLOGY.      By  E.   W.   SCRIPTURE,    Ph.D. 

(Leipzig).      With  124  Illustrations.     6s. 

"We  have  at  present  no  work  in  English  which  gives  in  so  compact  a  form  so 
comprehensive  a  view  of  the  subject." — Liverpool  Post. 

(34) 

SLEEP :  ITS  PHYSIOLOGY,  PATHOLOGY,  HYGIENE,  AND  PSYCH^- 
OLOGY.  By  MARIE  DE  MANACEINE  (St.  Petersburg).  Illustrated. 
33.  6d. 

"The  book  is  a  complete  and  wonderfully  interesting  exposition,  and  as  such 
ought  to  receive  a  hearty  welcome."— Scotsman. 

(35) 

THE    NATURAL     HISTORY    OF    DIGESTION.      By  A. 

LOCKHART   GILLESPIE,    M.D.;  F.R.C.P.   ED.,  F.R.S.   ED.      With 
a  large  number  of  Illustrations  and  Diagrams.     6s. 

"Dr.  Gillespie's  work  is  one  that  has  been  greatly  needed.  No  comprehensive 
collation  of  this  kind  exists  in  recent  English  literature.  All  the  important  work 
that  has  appeared  within  the  past  few  years  is  discussed  so  far  as  the  limits  of  the 
book  allow  of  discussion,  and  extremely  little  of  value  has  been  omitted.  Not  least 
interesting  are  the  accounts  of  the  author's  own  original  work."— American  Journal 
of  the  Medical  Sciences. 

(36) 

DEGENERACY:  ITS  CAUSES,  SIGNS,  AND  RESULTS.  By 
Professor  EUGENE  S.  TALBOT,  M.D.,  Chicago.  With  Illus- 
trations. 6s. 

"  The  author  is  bold,  original,  and  suggestive,  and  his  work  is  a  contribution  of 
real  and  indeed  great  value,  more  so  on  the  whole  than  anything  that  has  yet 
appeared  in  this  country."— -American  Journal  of  Psychology. 


(37) 

THE    RACES    OF    MAN:     A    SKETCH    OF    ETHNOGRAPHY 
AND  ANTHROPOLOGY.     ByJ.  DENIKER.  With  178  Illustrations.     6s. 

"Dr.  Deniker  has  achieved  a  success  which  is  well-nigh  phenomenal.  .  .  .  The 
well-chosen  and  carefully-executed  illustrations  greatly  enhance  the  value  of  the 
work,  which  we  do  not  hesitate  to  pronounce  the  best  small  treatise  on  its  subject 
which  has  appeared  of  recent  years  in  our  language."— British  Medical  Journal. 


(38) 

THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  RELIGION.  AN  EMPIRICAL 
STUDY  OF  THE  GROWTH  OF  RELIGIOUS  CONSCIOUSNESS.  By 
EDWIN  DILLER  STARBUCK,  PH.D.,  Assistant  Professor  of  Education, 
Leland  Stanford  Junior  University.  6s.  Second  Edition. 

"  There  is  here,  in  the  patient  gathering  and  careful  consideration  of  the  subjective 
facts  of  religious  life,  the  foundation  of  a  new  body  of  knowledge  which  will  find  its 
place  in  psychological  science  and  bear  practical  fruit  in  religious  education  and  in 
theology. " — Psychological  Review. 


(39) 

THE  CHILD :  A  STUDY  IN  THE  EVOLUTION  OF  MAN. 
By  Dr.  ALEXANDER  FRANCIS  CHAMBERLAIN,  M.A.,  PH.D., 
Lecturer  on  Anthropology  in  Clark  University,  Worcester,  Mass. 
With  Illustrations.  6s. 

"The  work  contains  much  curious  information,  and  should  be  studied  by  those 
who  have  to  do  with  children."— Sheffield  Daily  Telegraph. 


(40) 
THE    MEDITERRANEAN    RACE.      By    Professor    SERGI. 

With  over  100  Illustrations.     6s. 

"Obviously  all  this  requires  "a  great  deal  of  proving ;  we  can  only  say  that  Professor 
Sergi,  both  in  this  and  in  other  books,  brings  forward  large  quantities  of  new 
evidence  which  may  be  refuted,  but  cannot  be  ignored."— The  Times. 


(41) 
THE  STUDY  OF  RELIGION.      By  MORRIS  JASTROW,  JUN., 

PH.D.,  Professor  in  the  University  of  Pennsylvania.     6s. 

"It  is  no  hasty  compilation,  nor  is  it  an  attempt  to  throw  into  popular  form  the 
contents  of  better  books.  It  provides  precisely  the  kind  of  introduction  which  most 
people  need  to  the  comparative  study  of  religion  as  a  factor  in  the  evolution  of  human 
thought  and  culture." — Manchester  Guardian. 


(42) 

HISTORY  OF  GEOLOGY  AND  PALEONTOLOGY  TO 
THE  END  OF  THE  NINETEENTH  CENTURY.  By  KARL 
VON  ZITTEL.  Translated  by  MARIA  M.  OGILVIE-GORDON,  D.Sc., 
PH.D.  6s. 

"  All  geologists  are  grateful  to  Prof.  Zittel  for  his  thorough  and  painstaking  labour, 
for  his  fairness  and  breadth  of  view,  and  for  his  wonderful  grasp  of  the  whole  of  his 
science  ;  and  English-speaking  geologists  are  under  an  especial  debt  of  gratitude  to 
Mrs.  Ogilvie-Gordon  for  her  timely,  accurate,  and  well-written  translation. "-Mature. 

(43) 

THE  MAKING  OF  CITIZENS  :  A  STUDY  IN  COMPARATIVE 
EDUCATION.  By  R.  E.  HUGHES,  M.A.,  B.Sc.  6s. 

"Mr.  Hughes  gives  a  lucid  account  of  the  exact  position  of  education  in  England, 
Germany,  France,  and  United  States.  The  statistics  quoted  are  handled  so  as  to 
present  a  clear  and  attractive  picture  of  the  manner  in  which  one  of  the  greatest 
questions  now  at  issue  is  being  solved  both  at  home  and  abroad."— Standard. 


Crown  8vo,  about  350  pp.  each,  Cloth  Cover,  2/6  per  Vol.; 
Half-Polished  Morocco,  Gilt  Top,  55. 

Count  Tolstoy's  Works. 

The  following  Volumes  are  already  issued — 


A  RUSSIAN  PROPRIETOR. 

THE  COSSACKS. 

IVAN     ILYITCH,     AND     OTHER 

STORIES. 
MY  RELIGION. 
LIFE. 

MY  CONFESSION. 
CHILDHOOD,     BOYHOOD, 

YOUTH. 

THE  PHYSIOLOGY  OF  WAR. 
ANNA   KARENINA.      3/6. 


WHAT   TO   DO? 

WAR   AND   PEACE.      (4  vols.) 

THE  LONG  EXILE,  ETC. 

SEVASTOPOL. 

THE   KREUTZER  SONATA,  AND 

FAMILY   HAPPINESS. 
THE     KINGDOM     OF     GOD     IS 

WITHIN   YOU. 
WORK    WHILE  YE    HAVE    THE 

LIGHT. 
THE  GOSPEL  IN  BRIEF. 


Uniform  with  the  above — 
IMPRESSIONS  OF  RUSSIA.     By  Dr.  GEORG  BRANDES. 

Post  410,.  Cloth,  Price  is. 

PATRIOTISM  AND   CHRISTIANITY. 

To  which  is  appended  a  Reply  to  Criticisms  of  the  Work. 

By  COUNT  TOLSTOY. 

i/-  Booklets  by  Count  Tolstoy. 

Bound  in  White  Grained  Boards,  with  Gilt  Lettering. 


WHERE   LOVE  IS,. THERE   GOD 

IS  ALSO. 

THE   TWO   PILGRIMS. 
WHAT   MEN   LIVE  BY. 


THE  GODSON. 

IF  YOU  NEGLECT  THE  FIRE, 
YOU  DON'T  PUT  IT  OUT. 

WHAT  SHALL  IT  PROFIT  A  MAN  ? 


2/-   Booklets  by  Count  Tolstoy. 

NEW   EDITIONS,   REVISED. 

Small  I2mo,  Cloth,  with  Embossed  Design  on  Cover,  each  containing 

Two  Stories  by  Count  Tolstoy,  and  Two  Drawings  by 

H.  R.  Millar.    In  Box,  Price  2s.  each. 


Volume  I.  contains — 

WHERE    LOVE   IS,   THERE  GOD 

IS  ALSO. 
THE  GODSON. 

Volume  II.  contains — 

WHAT   MEN   LIVE   BY. 

WHAT     SHALL     IT     PROFIT     A 

MAN  ? 


Volume  III.  contains — 

THE  TWO  PILGRIMS. 

IF    YOU    NEGLECT    THE    FIRE, 

YOU  DON'T  PUT  IT  OUT. 
Volume  IV.  contains — 

MASTER  AND  MAN. 

.  Volume  V.  contains — 
TOLSTOY'S  PARABLES. 


THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LIMITED, 

LONDON   AND    NEWCASTLE-OX  -TV  M IK. 


THE    CONTEMPORARY    SCIENCE    SERIES. 

Edited  by  HAVELOCK  ELLIS. 

NEW    VOLUMES-      Crown  8vo,  Cloth,  Price  6s. 

MORALS:    Their   Psycho -Sociological    Bases. 

Translated  from  the  French  of  Duprat's  La  Morale, 
By  W.  J.  GREENSTREET,  M.A.,  Headmaster  of  Marling  School. 

The  field  of  psychological  research  has  been  widened  by  the  triple  alliance 
of  psychology,  physiology,  and  sociology — an  alliance  at  once  of  the  most 
intimate  and  fundamental  nature,  and  productive  of  far-reaching  results.  It 
need,  therefore,  occasion  no  surprise  that  among  the  volumes  of  a  scientific 
series  is  to  be  found  a  treatise  dealing  with  ethical  questions.  Recent  works 
on  ethics  have  not  been  numerous,  and  the  writers  seem  more  anxious  to  soar 
into  the  realm  of  lofty  thought  than  to  lay  the  foundations  of  work  that  will 
be  positive  and  lasting.  It  would  seem  that  the  time  has  come  for  a  system  of 
ethics  less  ambitious  in  its  aims,  more  restricted  in  its  scope,  and  based  on  a 
more  rigorous  method  of  treatment. 


Crown- 8vo,  Cloth,  Price  ds. 

THE     MAKING    OF    CITIZENS:    A  Study   in 
Comparative  Education. 

By  R.  E.  HUGHES,  M.A.,  B.Sc.,  Author  of  "Schools  at  Home  and  Abroad." 

It  is  instructive  and  interesting  to  have  a  complete  and  comprehensive 
account  of  both  onr  own  and  foreign  systems  of  education,  based  upon  an 
exhaustive  study  of  authoritative  and  official  data.  Mr.  Hughes  has  set  him- 
self the  task  of  showing  in  detail  and  by  a  series  of  pictures,  so  to  speak, 
what  the  four  leading  nations  of  the  world — England,  France,  Germany,  and 
America — are  doing  in  the  way  of  manufacturing  citizens.  The  primary  and 
secondary  systems  are  described  in  detail,  and  the  social  problems  of  national 
education  are  described  and  diagnosed. 


Crown  8vo,  Cloth,  Price  6s.     With  12  Portraits. 

History  of  Geology  and   Palaeontology  to  the  end 
of  the  Nineteenth  Century. 

By  KARL  VON  ZITTEL,  Professor  of  Geology  in  the  University  of  Munich. 

Translated  by  MARIE  M.  OGILVIE-GORDON,  D.Sc.,  Ph.D. 
This  work  is  recognised  as  the  most  complete  and  authoritative  history  of 
geology.     It  is  brought  down  to  the  end  of  the  nineteenth  century.     With  the 
author's  advice  and  assistance  the  work  has  been  slightly  abridged  by  the 
omission  of  the  less  generally  interesting  matter. 

Crown  8vo,  Cloth,  Price  6s. 
THE     STUDY    OF     RELIGION. 

By  MORRIS  JASTROW,  Jun.,  Professor  in  the  University  of  Pennsylvania. 
Professor  Jastrow,  who  is  Professor  of  Semitic  Languages  and  Religions, 
has  in  this  volume  traced  the  gradual  modern  developments  of  the  scientific 
study  of  religion,  discussing  this  study  in  its  bearings  on  other  related  studies, 
and  dealing  with  the  scientific  methods  of  carrying  it  on. 

THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  Co.,  LIMITED, 

LONDON    AND    NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


THE  MAKERS  OF  BRITISH  ART. 

SUCCESSFUL  LITERARY  VENTURE. 

A    NEW  SERIES    OF  MONOGRAPHS    OF 
BRITISH    ARTISTS. 


Each  volume  illustrated  with  Twenty  Full-page  Reproductions 
and  a  Photogravure  Portrait. 

Square  Crown  8vo,  Cloth,  Gilt  Top,  Deckled  Edges,  3^.  6d.  net. 


VOLUMES    READY. 

LANDSEERt  SIR  EDWIN.     By  the  EDITOR. 

"This  little  volume  may  rank  as  the  most  complete  account  of 
Landseer  that  the  world  is  likely  to  possess."—  Times. 

REYNOLDSt  SIR  JOSHUA.    By  ELSA  D'ESTERRE-KEELING. 

"To  the  series  entitled  'The  Makers  of  British  Art'  Miss  Elsa 
d'Esterre-Keeling  contributes  an  admirable  little  volume  on  Sir 
Joshua  Reynolds.  Miss  Reeling's  style  is  sprightly  and  epigrammatic, 
and  her  judgments  are  well  considered." — Daily  Telegraph. 

TURNER,  J.   M.  W.      By  ROBERT  CHIGXELL,  Author  of 
"The  Life  and  Paintings  of  Vicat  Cole,  R.A." 

"  Mr.  Chignell's  sketch  of  Turner's  life  and  career  is  comparatively 
brief.  But  it  is  not  superficial.  It  delineates  the  man  Turner  as  he 
was,  a  man  of  splendid  intelligence,  of  inexhaustible  kindness,  loyalty, 
and  generous  appreciation  of  the  work  of  his  fellow-artists." — Dai.y 

News. 

ROMNEYt  GEORGE.     By  SIR  HERBERT  MAXWELL,  Bart , 
F.R.S,  M.P. 

"  Likely  to  remain  the  best  account  of  the  painter's  life." — Athenaujn. 

WILKIE,  SIR  DAVID.     By  Professor  BAYNE. 

VOLUMES    IN    PREPARATION. 

CONSTABLE,  JOHN.     By  the  Right  Hon.  LORD  WINDSOR. 

MILLAIS,  SIR  JOHN  EVERETT.    By  J.  EADIE  REID,  Author 
of  "  The  Schools  and  Methods  of  Christian  Art." 

THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LIMITED, 
LONDON  AND  NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


The  Scott   Library. 

Cloth,  Uncut  Edges,  Gilt  Top.     Price  is.  6d.  per  Volume. 

May  also  be  had  in  the  following  Bindings  :— Half-Morocco,  gilt  top,  antique; 
•     ^  Red  Roan,  gilt  edges',  etc. 


VOLUMES  ALREADY  ISSUED— 


1  ROMANCE  OF  KING  ARTHUR. 

2  THOREAU'S  WALDEN. 

3  THOREAU'S  ['  WEEK." 

4  THOREAU'S  ESSAYS. 

5  ENGLISH  OPIUM-EATER. 

6  LANDOR'S  CONVERSATIONS. 

7  PLUTARCH'S  LIVES. 

8  RELIGIO  MEDICI,  &c. 

9  SHELLEY'S  LETTERS. 

10  PROSE  WRITINGS  OF  SWIFT. 

11  MY  STUDY  WINDOWS. 

12  THE  ENGLISH  POETS. 

13  THE  BIGLOW  PAPERS. 

14  GREAT  ENGLISH  PAINTERS. 

15  LORD  BYRON'S  LETTERS. 

16  ESSAYS  BY  LEIGH  HUNT. 

17  LONGFELLOW'S  PROSE. 

18  GREAT  MUSICAL  COMPOSERS. 

19  MARCUS  AURELIUS. 

20  TEACHING  OF  EPICTETUS. 

21  SENECA'S  MORALS. 

22  SPECIMEN  DAYS  IN  AMERICA. 

23  DEMOCRATIC  VISTAS. 

24  WHITE'S  SELBORNE. 

25  DEFOE'S  SINGLETON. 

26  MAZZINI'S  ESSAYS. 

2/  PROSE  WRITINGS  OF  HEINE. 
23  REYNOLDS'  DISCOURSES. 
1U  PAPERS  OP  STEELE  AND  ADDISON. 
33  BURNS'S  LETTERS. 

31  VOLSUNGA  SAGA. 

32  SARTOR  RESARTUS. 

33  WRITINGS  OF  EMERSON. 
31  LIFE  OF  LORD  HERBERT. 
35  ENGLISH  PROSE. 


36  IBSEN'S  PILLARS  OF  SOCIETY. 

37  IRISH  FAIRY  AND  FOLK  TALES. 

38  ESSAYS  OF  DR.  JOHNSON. 

39  ESSAYS  OF  WILLIAM  HAZLITT. 

40  LANDOR'S  PENTAMERON,  &c. 

41  POE'S  TALES  AND  ESSAYS. 

42  VICAR  OF  WAKEFIELD. 

43  POLITICAL  ORATIONS. 

44  AUTOCRAT  OF  THE  BREAKFAST- 

TABLE. 

45  POET     AT     THE     BREAKFAST- 

TABLE. 

46  PROFESSOR  AT  THE  BREAKFAST 

TABLE. 

47  CHESTERFIELD'S  LETTERS. 

48  STORIES  FROM  CARLETON. 

49  JANE  EYRE. 

50  ELIZABETHAN  ENGLAND. 

51  WRITINGS  OF  THOMAS  DAVIS. 

52  SPENCE'S  ANECDOTES. 

53  MORE'S  UTOPIA. 

54  SADFS  GU  LIST  AN. 

55  ENGLISH  FAIRY  TALES. 

56  NORTHERN  STUDIES. 

57  FAMOUS  REVIEWS. 

58  ARISTOTLE'S  ETHICS. 

59  PERICLES  AND  ASPASIA. 

60  ANNALS  OF  TACITUS. 

61  ESSAYS  OF  ELIA. 

62  BALZAC. 

63  DE  MUSSET'S  COMEDIES. 

64  CORAL  REEFS. 

65  SHERIDAN'S  PLAYS. 

66  OUR  VILLAGE. 

67  .MASTER  HUMPHREY'S  CLOCK 


THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LIMITED, 

'       LONDON   AND   NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


The  Scott   Library— continued. 


63  TALES  FROM  WONDERLAND. 

69  JERROLD'S  ESSAYS. 

70  THE  RIGHTS  OF  WOMAN. 

71  "THE  ATHENIAN  ORACLE." 

72  ESSAYS  OF  SAINTE-BEUVE. 

73  SELECTIONS  FROM  PLATO. 

74  HEINE'S  TRAVEL  SKETCHES. 

75  MAID  OF  ORLEANS. 

76  SYDNEY  SMITH. 

77  THE  NEW  SPIRIT. 

78  MALORY'S     BOOK     OF     MAR- 

VELLOUS ADVENTURES. 

79  HELPS'  ESSAYS  &  APHORISMS 

80  ESSAYS  OF  MONTAIGNE. 

81  THACKERAY'S  BARRY  LYNDON. 

82  SCHILLER'S  WILLIAM  TELL. 

83  CARLYLE'S  GERMAN  ESSAYS. 

84  LAMB'S  ESSAYS. 

85  WORDSWORTH'S  PROSE. 

86  LEOPARDI'S  DIALOGUES. 

87  THE  INSPECTOR-GENERAL. 

88  BACON'S  ESSAYS. 

89  PROSE  OF  MILTON. 

90  PLATO'S  REPUBLIC. 

91  PASSAGES  FROM  FROISSART. 

92  PROSE  OF  COLERIDGE. 

93  HEINE  IN  ART  AND  LETTERS. 

94  ESSAYS  OF  DE  QUINCEY. 

95  VASARI'S   LIVES  OF  ITALIAN 

PAINTERS. 

96  LESSING'S  LAOCOON. 

97  PLAYS  OF  MAETERLINCK. 


98  WALTON'S  COMPLETE  ANGLER 

99  LESSING'S  NATHAN  THE  WIL1-: 

100  STUDIES  BY  RENAN. 

101  MAXIMS  OF  GOETHE. 

102  SCHOPENHAUER. 

103  RENAN'S  LIFE  OF  JESUS. 

104  CONFESSIONS    OF     SAIXT 

AUGUSTINE. 

105  PRINCIPLES   OF   SUCCESS  TN" 

LITERATURE  (G.  H.  Lewes). 

106  WHAT  IS  ART?  (Tolstoy). 

107  WALTON'S  LIVES. 

108  RENAN'S  ANTICHRIST. 

109  ORATIONS  OF  CICERO. 

110  REFLECTIONS  ON  THE  REVOLU- 

TION IN  FRANCE  (E.  Burke). 

111  LETTERS  OF  THE    YOUNGER 

PLINY.     (Series  I.) 

112  Do.  (Series  II.) 

113  SELECTED    THOUGHTS    OF 

BLAISE  PASCAL. 

114  SCOTS  ESSAYISTS. 

115  J.  S.  MILL'S  LIBERTY. 

116  DESCARTES'  DISCOURSE  ON 

METHOD,  ETC. 

117  SAKUNTALA.    BY  KALIDASA, 

the  "Shakespeare  of  India. ' 

118  NEWMAN'S  (John  Henry  Cardiual) 

UNIVERSITY  SKETCHES.  • 

119  NEWMAN'S  (John  Henry  Cardinal) 

SELECT  ESSAYS. 


VAGABOND     PAPERS. 

BY  JOHN    FOSTER    FRASER. 
Foolscap  8vo,  Picture  Cover^  Price  One  Shilling. 

THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LIMITED, 
LONDON  AND   NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


The  Canterbury   Poets. 

EDITED  BY  WILLIAM  SHARP.     Cloth,  Cut  and  Uncut  Edges,  is.;  Red  Roan, 
Gilt  Edges,  2s.  6d. ;  Pad.  Morocco,  Gilt  Edges,  55. 

A  Superior  Edition  Bound  in  Art  Linen,  -with  Photogravure  Frontispiece,  2s. 


1  CHRISTIAN  YEAR 

2  COLERIDGE 

3  LONGFELLOW 

4  CAMPBELL 

5  SHELLEY 

6  WORDSWORTH 

7  BLAKE 

8  WHITTIER 

9  POE 

10  CHATTERTON 
n  BURNS.     Songs 

12  BURNS.     Poems 

13  MARLOWE 

14  KEATS. 

15  HERBERT 

16  HUGO 

17  COWPER 

18  SHAKESPEARE'S  POEMS,  etc. 

19  EMERSON 

20  SONNETS    OF    THIS    CEN- 

TURY 

21  WHITMAN 

22  SCOTT.     Lady  of  the  Lake,  etc. 

23  SCOTT.     Marmion,  etc. 

24  PRAED 


25  HOGG 

26  GOLDSMITH 

27  LOVE  LETTERS,  etc. 

28  SPENSER 

29  CHILDREN  OF  THE  POETS 

30  JONSON 

31  BYRON.     Miscellaneous 

32  BYRON.   Don  Juan 

33  THE  SONNETS  OF  EUROPE 

34  RAMSAY 

35  DOBELL 

36  POPE 

37  HEINE 

38  BEAUMONT  &  FLETCHER 

39  BOWLES,  LAMB,  etc. 

40  SEA  MUSIC 

41  EARLY  ENGLISH  POETRY 

42  HERRICK 

43  BALLADES  AND  RONDEAUS 

44  IRISH  MINSTRELSY 

45  MILTON'S  PARADISE  LOST 

46  JACOBITE  BALLADS 

47  DAYS  OF  THE  YEAR 

48  AUSTRALIAN  BALLADS 

49  MOORE 


THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LIMITED, 
LONDON  AND  NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


The  Canterbury   Poets— continued. 


50  BORDER  BALLADS 

51  SONG-TIDE 

52  ODES  OF  HORACE 

53  OSSIAN 

54  FAIRY  MUSIC 

55  SOUTHEY 

56  CHAUCER 

57  GOLDEN  TREASURY 

58  POEMS  OF  WILD  LIFE 

59  PARADISE  REGAINED 

60  CRABBE 

61  DORA  GREENWELL 

62  FAUST 

63  AMERICAN  SONNETS 

64  LANDOR'S  POEMS 

65  GREEK  ANTHOLOGY 

66  HUNT  AND  HOOD 

67  HUMOROUS  POEMS 

68  LYTTON'S  PLAYS 

69  GREAT  ODES 

70  MEREDITH'S  POEMS 

71  IMITATION  OF  CHRIST 

72  NAVAL  SONGS 

73  PAINTER  POETS 

74  WOMEN  POETS 

75  LOVE  LYRICS 

76  AMERICAN    HUMOROUS 

VERSE 

77  SCOTTISH  MINOR  POETS 

78  CAVALIER  LYRISTS 


79  GERMAN  BALLADS 

80  SONGS  OF  BERANGER 

81  RODEN  NOEL'S  POEMS 

82  SONGS  OF  FREEDOM 

83  CANADIAN  POEMS 

84  CONTEMPORARY     SCOT- 

TISH  VERSE 

85  POEMS  OF  NATURE 

86  CRADLE  SONGS 

87  BALLADS  OF  SPORT 

88  MATTHEW  ARNOLD 

89  CLOUGH'S  BOTHIE 

90  BROWNING'S  POEMS 

Pippa  Passes,  etc.     Vol.  I. 

91  BROWNING'S  POEMS 

A  Blot  in  the  'Scutcheon,  etc. 
Vol,  2. 

92  BROWNING'S  POEMS 

Dramatic  Lyrics.     Vol.  3.  . 

93  MACKAY'S    COVER'S    MIS- 

SAL 

94  HENRY  KIRKE  WHITE 

95  LYRA  NICOTIANA 

96  AURORA  LEIGH 

97  TENNYSON'S  POEMS 

In  Memoriam,  etc. 

98  TENNYSON'S  POEMS 

The  Princess,  etc. 

99  WAR  SONGS 

100  JAMES  THOMSON 

101  ALEXANDER  SMITH 

102  EUGENE  LEE-HAMILTON 


THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LIMITED, 
LONDON  AND   NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


Ibsen's  Prose   Dramas 

EDITED  BY  WILLIAM  ARCHER 

Complete  in  Five  Vols.     Crown  8vo,  Cloth,  Price  31.  6d.  each. 

Set  of  Five  Vols.,  in  Case,  17 's.  6d.  ;  in  Half  Morocco, 

in  Case,  32$.  6d. 


'  We  seem  at  last  to  be  shown  men  and  women  as  they  are  ;  and  at  first 
it  is  more  than  ive  can  endure.  .  .  .  All  Ibsen's  characters  speak  and  act 
as  if  they  "were  hypnotised,  and  under  their  creator  s  imperious  demand 
to  reveal  themselves.  There  never  was  such  a  mirror  held  up  to  nature 
before  i  it  is  too  terrible.  .  .  .  Yet  ive  must  return  to  Ibsen,  -with  his 
remorseless  surgery,  his  remorseless  electric-light,  until  we,  too,  have 
grown  strong  and  learned  to  face  the  naked — if  necessary,  the  flayed  and 
bleeding — reality' — SPEAKER  (  London). 

VOL.  I.  'A  DOLL'S  HOUSE,'  'THE  LEAGUE 
OF  YOUTH,'  and  'THE  PILLARS  OF  SOCIETY.' 
With  Portrait  of  the  Author,  and  Biographical  Introduc- 
tion by  WILLIAM  ARCHER. 

VOL.  II.  'GHOSTS,'  'AN  ENEMY  OF  THE 
PEOPLE,'  and  'THE  WILD  DUCK.'  With  an  Intro- 
ductory Note. 

VOL.  III.  'LADY  INGER  OF  OSTRAT,'  'THE 
VIKINGS  AT  HELGELAND,'  'THE  PRETEND- 
ERS.' With  an  Introductory  Note  and  Portrait  of  Ibsen. 

VOL.  IV.  'EMPEROR  AND  GALILEAN.'  With 
an  Introductory  Note  by  WILLIAM  ARCHER. 

VOL.  V.  'ROSMERSHOLM,'  'THE  LADY 
FROM  THE  SEA,'  '  HEDDA  GABLER.'  Translated 
by  WILLIAM  ARCHER.  With  an  Introductory  Note. 

The  sequence  of  the  plays  in  eachvolume  is  chronological ;  the  complete 
set  of  volumes  comprising  the  dramas  presents  them  in  chronological  order. 

THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LIMITED, 
LONDON  AND  N1UVCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


Great  Writers 

A  NEW  SERIES  OF  CRITICAL  BIOGRAPHIES. 

EDITED  BY  ERIC  ROBERTSON  AND  FRANK  T.  MARZIALS. 

A  Complete  Bibliography  to  each  Volume,  by  J.  P.  ANDERSON,  British 
Museum,  London. 

Cloth,  Uncut  Edges,  Gilt  Tof,    Price  is.  6d. 

VOLUMES  ALREADY  ISSUED. 

LIFE  OF  LONGFELLOW.     By  Professor  ERIC  S.  ROBERTSON. 
LIFE  OF  COLERIDGE.    By  HALL  CAINE. 
LIFE  OF  DICKENS.     By  FRANK  T.  MARZIALS. 
LIFE  OF  DANTE  GABRIEL  ROSSETTI.     By  J.  KNIGHT. 
LIFE  OF  SAMUEL  JOHNSON.     By  Colonel  F.  GRANT. 
LIFE  OF  DARWIN.     By  G.  T.  BETTANY. 
LIFE  OF  CHARLOTTE  BRONTE.     By  A.  BIRRELL. 
LIFE  OF  THOMAS  CARLYLE.     By  R.  GARNETT,  LL.D. 
LIFE  OF  ADAM  SMITH.     By  R.  B.  HALDANE,  M.P. 
LIFE  OF  KEATS.     By  W.  M.  ROSSETTI. 
LIFE  OF  SHELLEY.    By  WILLIAM  SHARP. 
L I FE  OF  SMOLLETT.    By  DAVID  HANNAY. 
LIFE  OF  GOLDSMITH.    By  AUSTIN  DOBSON. 
LIFE  OF  SCOTT.     By  Professor  YONGE. 
LIFE  OF  BURNS.     By  Professor  BLACKIE. 
LIFE  OF  VICTOR  HUGO.    By  FRANK  T.  MARZIALS. 
LIFE  OF  EMERSON.    By  RICHARD  GARNETT,  LL.D. 
LIFE  OF  GOETHE.    By  JAMES  SIME. 
LIFE  OF  CONGREVE.    By  EDMUND  GOSSE. 
LIFE  OF  BUNYAN.     By  Candn  VENABLES. 
LIFE  OF  CRABBE.     By  T.  E.  KEBBEL. 

,IFE  OF  HEINE.    By  WILLIAM  SHARP. 

.IFE  OF  MILL.     By  W.  L.  COURTNEY. 

,1FE  OF  SCHILLER.     By  HENRY  W.  NEVINSON. 

,IFE  OF  CAPTAIN  MARRYAT.    By  DAVID  HANNAY. 

.IFE  OF  LESS1NG.     By  T.  W.  ROLLESTON. 

,IFE  OF  MILTON.    By  R.  GARNETT,  LL.D. 

.IFE  OF  BALZAC.     By  FREDERICK  WEDMORE. 

.IFE  OF  GEORGE  ELIOT.     By  OSCAR  BROWNING. 

.IFE  OF  JANE  AUSTEN.     By  GOLDWIN  SMITH. 

,IFK  OF  BROWNING.     By  WILLIAM  SHARP. 
LIFE  OF  BYRON.     By  Hon.  RODEN  NOEL. 

,1FE  OF  HAWTHORNE.     By  MONCURE  D.  CONWAY. 

.IFE  OF  SCHOPENHAUER.     By  Professor  WALLACE. 
LIFE  OF  SHERIDAN.     By  LLOYD  SANDERS. 
LIFE  OF  THACKERAY.      By  HERMAN  MERIVALE  and  FRANK  T. 

MARZIALS. 

LIFE  OF  CERVANTES.    By  H.  E.  WATTS. 
LIFE  OF  VOLTAIRE.     By  FRANCIS  ESPINASSE. 

i. IFE  OF  LEIGH  HUNT.     By  COSMO  MONKHOUSE. 

LIFE  OF  WHITTIER.     By  W.  J   LINTON. 
LIFE  OF  RENAN.     By  FRANCIS  ESPINASSE. 
LIFE  OF  THOREAU.    By  H.  S.  SALT. 


LIBRARY  EDITION  OF  'GREAT  WRITERS/ Demy  8vo,  as.  6d. 


THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LIMITED, 
LONDON  AND  NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


COMPACT  AND  PRACTICAL. 
In  Limp  Cloth  ;  for  the  Pocket.     Price  One  Shilling. 

THE    EUROPEAN 

CONVERSATION  BOOKS. 


FRENCH  ITALIAN 

SPANISH  GERMAN 

NORWEGIAN 

CONTENTS. 

Hints  to  Travellers — Everyday  Expressions — Arriving  ct 
and  Leaving  a  Railway  Station — Custom  House  Enquiries — In 
a  Train — At  a  Buffet  and  Restaurant — At  an  Hotel— Paying-  an 
Hotel  Bill— Enquiries  in  a  Town — On  Board  Ship — Embarking 
and  Disembarking — Excursion  by  Carriage — Enquiries  as  to 
Diligences — Enqitiries  as  to  Boats — Engaging  Apartments- 
Washing  List  and  Days  of  Week — Restaurant  Vocabulary— 
Telegrams  and  Letters^  etc.,  etc. 


Thfe  contents  of  these  little  handbooks  are  so  arranged  as  to 
permit  direct  and  immediate  reference.  All  dialogues  or  enquiries  not 
considered  absolutely  essential  have  been  purposely  excluded,  nothing 
being  introduced  which  might  confuse  the  traveller  rather  than  assist 
him.  A  few  hints  are  given  in  the  introduction  which  will  be  found 
valuable  to  those  unaccustomed  to  foreign  travel. 

THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LIMITED, 
LONDON  AND  NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


NEW   ENGLAND    LIBRARY. 

QRAVURE   EDITION. 

PRINTED  ON  ANTIQUE  PAPER.     2s.  6d.  PER  VOL. 

Each  Volume  with  a  Frontispiece  in  Photogravure, 

By   NATHANIEL  HAWTHORNE. 

THE  SCARLET  LETTER. 

THE  HOUSE  OF  THE  SEVEN  GABLES; 

THE  BLITHEDALE  ROMANCE. 

TANGLEWOOD  TALES. 

TWICE-TOLD  TALES. 

A  WONDER-BOOK  FOR  GIRLS  AND  BOYS. 

OUR  OLD  HOME 

MOSSES  FROM  AN  OLD  MANSE. 

THE  SNOW  IMAGE. 

TRUE  STORIES  FROM  HISTORY  AND  BIOGRAPHY, 

THE  NEW  ADAM  AND  EVE. 

LEGENDS  OF  THE  PROVINCE  HOUSE. 

By  OLIVER  WENDELfc   HOLMES. 

THE  AUTOCRAT  OF  THE  BREAKFAST-TABLE. 
THE  PROFESSOR  AT  THE  BREAKFAST-TABLE. 
THE  POET  AT  THE  BREAKFAST-TABLE. 
ELSIE  VENNER. 

By   HENRY  THOREAU, 

ESSAYS  AND  OTHER  WRITINGS. 
WALDEN;   OR,  LIFE  IN  THE  WOODS, 
A  WEEK  ON  THE  CONCORD. 

THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LIMITED, 
LONDON  AND  NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


EVERY-DAY  HELP  SERIES 

OF  USEFUL  HANDBOOKS.     Price  Bd.  each, 

OR   IN   ROAN    BINDING,   PRICE  Is. 

Contributors— J.  LANGDON  DOWN,  M.D.,  F.R.C.P.;  HENRY 
POWER,  M.B.,  F.R.C.S.;  J.  MORTIMER-GRANVILLE,  M.D.; 
J.  CRICHTON  BROWNE,  M.D.,  LL.D.;  ROBERT  FARQUHARSON, 
M.D.  Edin.;  W.  S.  GREENFIELD,  M.D.,  F.R.C.P.;  and  others. 

1.  How  to  Do  Business.     A  Guide  to  Success  in  Life. 

2.  How  to  Behave.     Manual  of  Etiquette  and  Personal  Habits. 

3.  How  tO  Write.     A  Manual  of  Composition  and  Letter  Writing. 

4.  HOW  tO  Debate.     With  Hints  on  Public  Speaking. 

5.  Don't :  Directions  for  avoiding  Common  Errors  of  Speech. 

6.  The  Parental  Don't :  Warnings  to  Parents. 

7.  Why  Smoke  and  Drink.    By  James  Parton. 

8.  Elocution.     By  T.  R.  W.   Pearson,  M.A.,  of  St.  Catharine's 

College,  Cambridge,  and  F.  W.  Waithman,  Lecturers  on  Elocution. 

9.  The  Secret  of  a  Clear  Head. 
1O.  Common  Mind  Troubles. 

'  11.  The  Secret  of  a  Good  Memory, 

12.  Youth:  Its  Care  and  Culture. 

13.  The  Heart  and  its  Function. 

14.  Personal  Appearances  in  Health  and  Disease 

15.  The  House  and  its  Surroundings. 

16.  Alcohol:  Its  Use  and  Abuse. 

17.  Exercise  and  Training. 
13.  Baths  and  Bathing. 

19.  Health  in  Schools. 

20.  The  Skin  and  its  Troubles. 

21.  How  to  make  the  Best  of  Life. 

22.  Nerves  and  Nerve-Troubles. 

23.  The  Sight,  and  How  to  Preserve  it. 

24.  Premature  Death:  Its  Promotion  and  Prevention. 

25.  Change,  as  a  Montal  Restorative. 

26.  The  Gentle  Art  of  Nursing  the  Sick. 

27.  The  Care  of  Infants  and  Young  Children. 

28.  Invalid  Feeding,  with  Hints  on  Diet. 

29.  Event-day  Ailments,  and  How  to  Treat  Them 

30.  ThrlTty  Housekeeping. 

31.  Home  Cooking. 

32.  Flowers  and  Flower  Culture. 

33.  Sleep  and  Sleeplessness. 

34.  The  Story  of  Life. 


THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  .LIMITED, 
LONDON  AND  NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


THE  MUSIC  STORY  SERIES. 

A  SERIES  OF  LITERARY-MUSICAL  MONOGRAPHS. 

Edited  by  FREDERICK  J.   CROWEST, 

Author  of  "  The  Great  Tone  Poets." 

Illustrated  with  Photogravure  and  Collotype  Portraits,  Half-tone  and  Line 
Pictures,  Facsimiles,  etc. 

Square  Crown  8vo,   Cloth,  js.  6d.  net. 


VOLUMES   NOW   READY. 

THE  STORY  OF  ORATORIO.  'By  ANNIE  W.  PATTER- 
SON, B.A.,  Mus.  Doc. 

"Written  in  a  bright  style,  in  which  technicalities  are  as  much  as 
possible  avoided,  Miss  Patterson's  monograph  should  find  favour 
with  the  musical  public." — Scotsman. 

THE  STORY  OF  NOTATION;  By  C.  F.  ABDY  WILLIAMS, 
M.A.,  Mus.  Bac. 

NEXT  VOLUME. 

THE     STORY     OF     THE     ORGAN.       By     C.     F.     ABDY 

WILLIAMS,  M.A.,  Author  of  "Bach"  and  "Handel"  ("Master 
Musicians'  Series  "). 

IN     PREPARATION. 

THE  STORY  OF  THE  PIANOFORTE.     By  ALGERNON  S. 

ROSE,  Author  of  "  Talks  with  Bandsmen." 

THE  STORY  OF  HARMONY.  By  EUSTACE  J.  BREAK- 

SPEARE,  Author  of  "  Mozart,"  "Musical  ^Esthetics,"  etc. 

THE    STORY    OF    THE    ORCHESTRA.      By    STEWART 

MACPHERSON,   Fellow  and  Professor,  Royal  Academy  of  Music  ; 
Conductor  of  the  Westminster  Orchestral  Society. 

THE  STORY  OF  CHAMBER  MUSIC.  By  N.  KILBURN, 
Mus.  BAG.  (Cantab.),  Conductor  of  the  Middlesbrough,  Sunderland, 
and  Bishop  Auckland  Musical  Societies. 

THE  STORY  OF  BIBLE  MUSIC.  By  ELEONORE 
D'ESTERRE-KEELING,  Author  of  "The  Musicians'  Birthday 
Book." 

THE  STORY  OF  THE  VIOLIN.  By  A  PRACTICAL 
VIOLINIST. 

THE  STORY  OF  CHURCH  MUSIC.     By  THE  EDITOR. 
ETC.,   ETC.,  ETC. 

THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LIMITED, 
LONDON  AND  NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


MUSICIANS'  WIT,  HUMOUR,  AND 
ANECDOTE: 

BEING    ON  DITS   OF    COMPOSERS,    SINGERS,    AND 
INSTRUMENTALISTS    OF    ALL    TIMES. 

By   FREDERICK    J.    CROWEST, 

Author  of  "The  Great  Tone  Poets,"  "  The  Story  of  British  Music," 
Editor  of  "The  Master  Musicians"  Series,  etc.,  etc. 


Profusely  Illustrated  with  Quaint  Drawings  by 
J.    P.    DONNE. 

•5  

In  One  Volume — Crown  %vo,  Cloth,  Richly  Gilt,  Price  3/6. 


Among  the  hundreds  of  stories  abounding  in  wit  and  pointed 
repartee  which  the  volume  contains,  will  be  found  anecdotes  of 
famous  musicians  of  all  countries  and  periods. 


TOLSTOY:  His  Life  and  Works. 

By   JOHN    C.    KENWORTHY, 
AN  INTIMATE  FRIEND  OF  THE  GREAT  RUSSIAN  WRITER. 


One  Volume,  Crown  Svo,  256  pages,  Richly  Bound,  containing 
Portraits,  Facsimile  Letter,  Views,  etc. 

PRICE     SIX    SHILLINGS. 

THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LTD., 

LONDON   AND   NEWCASTLE-ON-TYNE. 


The  Emerald   Library. 

Crown  8vo,  Gilt  Top,  Half  Bound  in  Dark  Green  Ribbed 

Cloth,  with  Light  Green  Cloth  Sides,  2s.  each. 

flirnaby  Rudge 
Old  Curiosity  Shop 

Knight  of  19th  Century 
Caudle's  Lectures 

Old  Helmet 
Bleak  House 

Pickwick  Papers 

Jack  Hinton 

Cecil  Dreeme 

Nicholas  Nickleby 

Bret  ilarte 

Melbourne  House 

Oliver  Twist 

Ingoldsby  Legends 

Wuthering  Heights 

Martin  Chuzzlewit 

Handy  Andy 

The  Days  of  Bruce 

Sketches  by  Boz 

Lewis  Arundel 

The  Vale  of  Cedars 

OliYe 

Guy  Mannering 

Hunchback  of  Notre 

The  Ogilvies 

Rob  Roy 

Dame 

Ivanhoa 

Fortunes  of  Nigel 

Vashti 

Kenilworth 

Man  in  the  Iron  Mask 

The  Caxtons 

Jacob  Faithful 

Great  Composers 

Harold,  Last  of  the 

Peter  Simple 

Louise  de  la  Valliere 

Saxon  Kings 

Paul  Clifford 

Great  Painters 

Toilers  of  the  Sea 

Eugene  Aram 

Rory  O  More 

What  Can  She  Do? 

Krnest  Malt  ravers 

Arabian  Nights 

New  Border  Tales 

Alice  ;  or,  The  Mys- 

Swiss Family  Robinson 

Frank  Fairlegh 

teries 

Andersen's  Fairy  Tales 

Zanoni 

Rienzi 

Three  Musketeers 

Macaria 

Pelham 

Twenty  Years  After 

Inez 

The  Last  Days  of 

Vicomte  de  Bragelonne 

Conduct  and  Duty 

Pompeii 

Monte  Cristo—  Dantes 

Windsor  Castle 

The  Scottish  Chiefs 

,,  Revenge  of  Dantes 

Hard  Times 

Wilson's  Tales 

The  Newcomes 

Tower  of  London 

The  Fair  God 

Life  of  Robert  Moffat 

John  Halifax,  Gentle- 

Miss  Bedford's 

Life  of  Gladstone 

Westward  Ho  1     [man 

Mystery 

Cranferd 

Lavengro 

A  Mountain  Daisy 

North  and  South 

It  is  Never  Too  Late 

Hazel;  or.Perilpoint 

Life  of  Gen.  Gordon 

to  Mend 

Lighthouse 

Lincoln  and  Gartield 

Two  Years  Ago 

Vicar  of  Wakefield 

Great  Modern  Women 

In  His  Steps 

Prince  of  the  House 

Henry  Esmond 

Crucifixion  of  Phillip 

of  David 

Alton  Locke 

Strong 

Wide,  Wide  World 

.    Life  of  Livingstone 

His  Brother's  Keeper 

Village  Tales 

Life  of  Grace  Darling 

Robert  Hardy's  Seven 

Ben-Hur 

White's  Seibome 

Days,   and  Malcom 

Uncle  Tern's  Cabin 

Tales  of  the  Covenan- 

Ktrk (in  1  vol.) 

Robinson  Crusoe 

ters 

Richard  Bruce 

The  White  Slave 

Barriers  Burned  Away 

The  Twentieth  Door 

Charles  O'Maltey 
Midshipman  Easy 

Opening  a  Chestnut 
Burr 

House  of  the    Seven 
Gables 

Bride  of  Lammermoor 

Pendennis 

Elsie  Venner 

Heart  of  Midlothian 

David  Copperfield 

The  Romany  Rye 

Last  of  the  Barons 

Luck  of  Barry  Lyndon 

Little  Dorrit 

.  Old  Mortality 

St.  Elmo 

The  Scarlet  Letter 

Tom  Cringle's  Log 

Son  of  Porthos 

Mary  Barton 

Cruise  of  the  Midge 

Stanley  and  Africa 

Home  Influence 

Colleen  Bawn 

Life  of  Wesley 

The  Mother's  Recom- 

Valentine Vox 
Night  and  Morning 

Life  of  Spurgeon 
For  Lust  of  Gold 

pense 
Tennyson's  Poems 

Bunyan 

Wooing  of  Webster 

Harry  Coverdale's 

Foxe's  Book  of  Mar- 

At the  Mercy  of  Ti- 

Courtship 

tyrs 

berius 

The  Bible  in  Spain 

Mansfield  Park 

Countess   of   Rudol- 

Handbook  of  House- 

lAst of  the  Mohicans 

stadt 

keeping 

Poor  Jack 

Consuelo 

The  Dead  Secret 

The  Lamplighter 

Two  Years  before  the 

^ueen  Victoria 

Jane  Eyre 

Mast 

Martin  Rattler 

Pillar  of  Fire 

Fair  Maid  of  Perth 

Ungava 

Throne  of  David 

Peveril  of  the  Peak 

The  Coral  Island 

Dombey  and  Son 

Shirley 

Adam  Bede 

Vanity  Fair 

Queechy 

The  Young  Fur-Traders 

I  life!  ice 
Beulah 
Harry  Lorreojaer 
Essays  of  Elia 
Sheridan's  Plays 
Waverley 
Quentin  Durward 
Talisman 

Naomi;  or,  the  Last 
Days  of  Jerusalem 
Little  Women  and 
Good  Wives 
11  vpatia 
Viilette 
Rath 
Agatha's  Husband 

The  Virginians 
A  Tale  of  Two  Cities 
Scenes  of  Clerical  Life 
The  Mill  on  the  Floss 
Danesbury  House 
A  Life  for  a  Life 
Christmas  Books 

From  Jest  to  Earnest 

Head  of  the  Family 

London:  THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  Co.,  LTD. 


THE  WORLD'S  GREAT  NOVELS, 

A  series  of  acknowledged  masterpieces  by  the  most  eminent  writers 
of  fiction.  Excellent  paper,  large  type,  handsomely  and  strongly 
bou?id  in  Russia  Red  Cloth,  these  books  are  admirably  suited  either  for 
Presentation  or  for  a  permanent  place  in  the  library,  whi!e  the  low 
price  brings  them  within  reach  of  every  class  of  readers. 

Large  Crown  8vo.     Hundreds  of  Pages.     Numerous  Illustrations. 
3s.   6cl.  per  Vol. 


Adam  Bede,  By  George  Eliot.  '  With  Six  Full-page  Illustra- 
tions by  S.  H.  Vedder  and  J.  Jellicoe. 

Anna  Karenina,  By  Count  Tolstoy.  With  Ten  Illustrations 
by  Paul  Frenzeny,  and  a  Frontispiece  Portrait  of  Count  Tolstoy. 

Chicot,  the  Jester  (La  Dame  de  Monsoreau).  By  Alexandre 
Dumas.  New  and  Complete  Translation.  With  Nine  Full-page  Illus- 
trations by  Frank  T.  Merrill. 

Count  of  Monte-Cristo,  The,  By  Alexandre  Dumas.  With 
Sixteen  Full-page  Illustrations  by  Frank  T.  Merrill. 

David  Copperfield,  By  Charles  Dickens.  With  Forty  Illus- 
trations by  Hablot  K.  Browne  ("Phiz")*. 

Forty-Five  Guardsmen,  The,  By  Alexandre  Dumas.  New 
and  Complete  Translation.  With  Nine  Full-page  Illustrations  by  Frank 
T.  Merrill. 

Ivanhoe,  By  Sir  Walter  Scott.  With  Eight  Full-page  Illustra- 
tions by  Hugh  M.  Eaton. 

Jane  Eyre,  By  Charlotte  Bronte.  With  Eight  Full-page 
Illustrations,  and  Thirty-two  Illustrations  in  the  Text,  and  Photogravure 
Portrait  of  Charlotte  Bronte. 

John  Halifax,  Gentleman,  By  Mrs.  Craik.  With  Eight  Full- 
page  Illustrations  by  Alice  Barber  Stephens. 

Marguerite    de    Valois,     By   Alexandre   Dumas.     New    and 

Complete  Translation.     With  Nine  Full-paqe  Illustrations  by  Frank  T. 
Merrill.  ^J 

Miserables,   Les,     By  Victor  Hugo.     With   Twelve  Full-page 

Illustrations. 
Notre  Dame,     By  Victor  Hugo.     With  many  Illustrations. 

Three  Musketeers,  The,  By  Alexandre  Dumas.  With 
Twelve  Full-page  Illustrations  by  T.  Eyre  Macklin* 

Twenty  Years  After.  By  Alexandre  Dumas.  With  numerous 
Illustrations. 

Vicomte  de  Bragelonne,  The,  By  Alexandre  Dumas.  New 
and  Complete  Translation.  With  Eight  Full-page  Illustraiions. 

THE  WALTER  SCOTT  PUBLISHING  COMPANY,  LIMITED, 
LONDON  AND  NEWCASTLE-ON.TYNK. 


UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA  LIBRARY 
This  book  is  DUE  on  the  last  date  stamped  below. 


,30605!  CM 


, 


29Ju!'57B 
REC'D  LD 

JUL  29  1957 


3Jan'6lBSX 


DEC  4    t&Q 


21-100m-12,'46(A2012sl6)4126 


REC'D 

APR  20  1959 

270ct59|RB 
REC'D  LD 

OCT  2  7  1959 

50EC'60RT 


REC'D  CD 
JUN    51961 


YB  2268 1