Skip to main content

Full text of "The Nature Of Knowing"

See other formats


THE BOOK WAS 
DRENCHED 



<s^ - 

w ^ 

[<OU 164482 ^ 
>Qi ~ ;o 



OSMANIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARY 

l No. &/ &* /^^Accession No. 

Author 




This book should be returned on or before the date last marked below 



THE NATURE OF 
KNOWING 



THE NATURE OF 
KNOWING 



By 

R. I. AARON 



M.A. (Wales), D.Phil. (Oxon.) 

Of University College, Swansea 

Sometime Fellow of the University of Wales 



LONDON 

WILLIAMS & NORGATE LTD 
1930 



PR1NTFD IN GRFAT BRIT UN' BY 
UNVVIN BROTHERS LIMIJLD, LONDON AND \\OKING 



Contents 
PREFACE page 7 

INTRODUCTION 9 

THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 

Section i. The Nai've View 19 

Section 2. Critical Theories 24 

Section 3. A Further Critical Position 42 

DISCURSIVE REASONING 

Section [. The Prior Knowledge of Prin- 
ciples 69 
Section 2. The 'Experience' Presupposed 82 
Section 3. The Nature of Mediate Know- 
ledge 95 

INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 

Section i. 'Transcendent' Knowledge 121 

Section 2. The Intuitive Character of the 

Knowing Act 138 

CONCLUSION 151 



Preface 

IN the following pages I have set forth in essay form the fruit 
of six years' research upon the problem of knowing. These 
researches were pursued for the most part at Oxford, and the 
present essay is a restatement in, I hope, more explicit and more 
adequate terms of the argument contained in a dissertation 
which I submitted for the degree of D.Phil, in 1926. I decided 
not to publish the dissertation itself. It was lengthy, cumber- 
some, and most serious defect of all contained so much 
historical detail as to bewilder the reader and to distract his 
attention from my main argument. I thought it wiser, there- 
fore, to discard the historical matter altogether, especially as 
most of it was already familiar enough to any serious student 
of philosophy. In the argument of the present essay there are, 
for this reason* few historical references ; though a reader who 
is acquainted with the philosophical speculations both of the 
past and of the present will quickly realize my indebtedness 
to others. As to the past, I find my debt greatest to Plato, 
Aristotle, Descartes, Spinoza, and Kant. 

I have been singularly fortunate in my teachers throughout. 
In connection with the present work I have to express my 
thanks for suggestions to Professor J. A. Smith and the Master 
of Balliol (Dr. A. D. Lindsay), the examiners of my disserta- 
tion; to Professor H. A. Prichard; to my colleague, Dr. A. C. 
Ewing; to Professor II. H.Joachim; and, finally, to the Provost 
of Oriel (Dr. W. D. Ross). The three latter gentlemen have 
aided me very considerably, and I am much obliged to them. 
My thanks are due to my publishers and their reader for 
valuable guidance; also to my sister, Miss E. G. Aaron, for 
helping with the manuscript and proofs. Finally, I am grateful 
to the Court of the University of Wales for electing me a 
Fellow of the University, and to the Provost and Fellows of 
Oriel College, Oxford, for a special research grant. 

R. I. AARON 

YNYSTAWE, SWANSEA 
December 1929 



Introduction 

IT will be the aim of this essay to describe as accurately as 
possible the nature of knowing. We say 'knowing' rather than 
'knowledge' because the two terms are not always synonymous. 
In everyday language the term 'knowledge* may mean one of 
three things: firstly, the actual knowing of the object; secondly, 
the whole object known; and thirdly, a stock of information 
possessed by the mind which it can recall whenever the neces- 
sary conditions are realized. In this essay, our immediate con- 
cern is with knowledge in the first sense. It is our purpose to 
describe knowing; though, obviously, frequent reference to 
knowledge in the other two senses will be necessary. 

Now the strictest description would be definition, but no 
satisfactory definition of knowing is available. This fact may 
be attributed tt> one of two causes. It may be held that knowing 
is something elemental and therefore cannot be defined in 
terms of anything other than itself. For in definition so it may 
be argued we express the essential feature or features of the 
thing defined in terms whose meaning is already familiar to us. 
Thus it belongs to the essential nature of a triangle that it 
should consist of three straight lines in certain definite spatial 
relations, and the definition of a triangle is only possible when 
we know, amongst other things, the meaning of the phrase 'a 
straight line*. Now if I were to try to define knowing by saying 
that it is, for example, the co-presence of mind and object, this 
would presuppose a knowledge of what I wanted to define, 
because, if I were asked w r hat the word 'mind' signified here, 
the only possible answ r er would be that mind in this context is 
the knowing pow r er; that is to say, my definition would be 
circular. And in this manner, since knowledge is something 
elemental, every attempt at its definition, it may be argued, 
would necessarily involve the use of the very term we wish to 
define, and, in so far, would prove invalid. 

In the second place, the mind seeks definitions because it 
hopes thereby to gain both in thought and statement the 
precision that it needs. But this clearly implies that definition 



10 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

is possible only when we already possess a certain acquaintance 
and even familiarity with the thing to be defined. Definition is 
the crystallization of our thoughts about any matter by expres- 
sing them in terms which are already precisely fixed in our 
minds. It can occur only at an advanced stage of knowing. 
Now with regard to knowledge of knowing itself we can hardly 
claim to be at a sufficiently advanced stage to attempt definition. 
For though we are all acquainted with knowing at least, we 
believe that we know frequently yet when we begin to reflect 
we find it difficult to make clear to ourselves the nature of this 
knowing, and the more we reflect, the more difficult does the 
task become. None the less, in order to define knowledge it 
would seem necessary for us to possess some prior notion of 
what it essentially is, for it is only then that we can attempt to 
clarify this notion still further by definition, if, that is to say, 
we grant that definition is at all possible in this case. But at 
our present uncritical stage, we have so vague a notion of what 
we mean by knowing that immediate definition is out of the 
question. For these reasons, therefore, it is impossible at this 
point simply to define knowing and, having thus completed our 
task, put down the pen. 

Realizing that definition is here out of the question, we must 
proceed to our goal, namely, the accurate description of know- 
ledge, by a different route. The procedure we propose to adopt 
is the careful scrutiny of what are taken to be examples of 
knowing in order that by such scrutiny we may, if possible, 
lay bare the nature of the knowing involved. We shall, there- 
fore, find it necessary as we proceed to subject such instances 
of knowing to a critical examination, and to inquire into the 
validity of the claims made for them. We shall search for those 
experiences which are in the fullest and completest sense 
instances of knowing, since it is the scrutiny of such that will 
reveal most to us about its inmost nature. Having discovered 
such examples, we shall then seek by fair and accurate analysis 
to describe the knowing contained therein. 

Thfcs it will be understood that our primary aim is not to 
explain knowing, but rather to describe it. The question, 'How 



INTRODUCTION u 

does knowing occur?' can be answered in one of two ways. 
Firstly, we may describe the process or processes present in 
the mind when it knows ; secondly, we may set forth a thorough- 
going metaphysic so as to show the ultimate source of such 
knowing and the nature of the universe within which alone 
knowing can become possible. The second answer would 
provide an explanation of knowledge, whereas the first would 
be descriptive only. Now it is not the primary aim of this essay 
to supply the reader with 'explanations' in this sense, nor to 
answer these profounder questions. The attitude we intend 
to adopt is that of 'first things first' ; since it seems foolish and 
rash to seek for the metaphysical explanation of that which 
as yet we cannot even describe. At the same time, we readily 
grant the possibility that no completely satisfactory account 
of knowledge can ultimately be given without a metaphysic of 
some kind or qther. The distinction, that is to say, between 
description and explanation may not hold in the last resort; 
every description to be complete may also have to be an explana- 
tion. Nevertheless, as we begin on our search for an adequate 
description of knowledge, it is as well to point out some of the 
more obvious truths first, and to grasp firmly the things that 
lie, comparatively speaking, ready to hand, before venturing 
into the cavernous depths of metaphysics. For then we shall at 
least safeguard ourselves against the unhappy fate of those who 
plunge heedlessly into the gloomy darkness of deep speculation 
without first securing for their guidance such illumination as a 
careful study of what lies in the open can provide. We there- 
fore make no apology for the fact that this essay is mostly 
'surface' work. The reader should not look to it for ultimate 
explanations. 

But these words must not be taken to mean that the limited 
task before us is an easy one ; on the contrary, real difficulties 
present themselves from the first. No sooner do we begin upon 
our search than we meet with a serious problem, namely, what 
may and what may not be taken for granted at the outset. 

It is sometimes supposed that philosophy is unlike th$ par- 
ticular sciences in that it takes nothing for granted. This state- 



12 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

ment, however, is not absolutely true. Philosophy, perhaps, 
takes less for granted than does any particular science ; never- 
theless, it always begins by assuming certain positions as yet 
undemonstrated. In this matter of epistemology, for example, 
unless one is a confirmed and complete sceptic, one must take 
the fact of knowledge itself for granted ; while actually, as has 
been pointed out long since, even the sceptic who flatly and 
explicitly denies this fact is at the very moment of his denial 
implicitly presupposing it. For he is claiming to know that there 
is no such thing as real knowledge. Either he does not know this, 
and then his flat denial becomes impossible; or he does, and 
then he himself is possessed of knowledge a fact that contra- 
dicts his own denial of it. The case of the agnostic who doubts 
without definitely denying the actuality of knowledge is different. 
He may refuse to assert anything whatever, preferring to sus- 
pend his judgement throughout. He would not then be pre- 
supposing the fact of knowledge ; but neither would any inquiry 
ever be possible in his case. To carry out an inquiry we must 
make assertions which we hold or imply to be true. 1 In order 
to philosophize significantly, therefore, it is necessary to take 
knowledge for granted from the outset ; we already believe that 
the human mind is capable of knowing. 

Thus we find it essential in an effort to describe the nature 
of knowing to start from a basis which is taken as true, without 
being demonstrated to be such. Obviously, we should assume 
in this way only the barest minimum necessary, and we must, 
furthermore, make clear and definite to ourselves what exactly 
it is which we do thus assume. In the first place, as we have seen, 
we take for granted the fact of knowing. Our quest is one into 
which a person who refuses to make this assumption cannot 
enter. We may be sceptical about many epistemological tenets 

1 Some of these assertions may be mere opinions about which we 
do not feel completely certain. Yet judgements of probability pre- 
suppose some certainty. And, in any case, when we express an 
opinion, we imply that it may be true that is to say, that we may 
have gained knowledge, which in turn implies a belief in the possi- 
bility of our gaining knowledge. 



INTRODUCTION 13 

which are now generally accepted as true, but we cannot be 
sceptical about the fact of knowing itself if we wish to proceed 
with our inquiry ; for by such scepticism we should be depriving 
ourselves of the one faculty whereby the pursuit of the inquiry 
becomes possible. If we assert at the outset that we cannot 
know, it is then foolish to try to discover w r hat knowledge could 
ever be, since the discovering would itself be an example of 
knowing. 

Belief in the actuality of knowing as a fact of human expe- 
rience is thus essential for the further progress of our inquiry; 
but if we hold this belief it follows that we already know some- 
thing as to the real nature of knowing. The truth seems to be 
that, however far back we go, the inquiry into its nature is never 
begun from a point at which we know absolutely nothing about 
it, as if our minds were in this respect vacant and empty, 
waiting to be filled. On the contrary, since in our inquiry we 
propose to proceed by seeking for valid examples of knowing 
amongst our experiences, we could never begin on this task did 
we not already possess some method whereby we might test 
the various experiences, so as to discover which were true 
instances of knowing and which not. This method may be 
modified frequently as we proceed, but the capacity for testing 
must be in our possession from the outset of our inquiry; for 
otherwise \ve should be incapable of recognizing any instance 
of kno\\ing to be such. And, as is evident on reflection, what 
we really mean here is that we could never pick out a single 
instance of knowing did we not know beforehand some one or 
many of its characteristics. 

Now what characteristic or characteristics do we look for in 
an experience when we seek to discover whether it be an 
instance of knowing or not? First of all, clearly, we demand that 
the experience should give us assurance amounting to con- 
viction. Here, it would seem, is as universal a feature of know- 
ing as any. Knowledge is always marked by unwavering con- 
viction, and if we doubt, however slightly, we realize that our 
state then qua doubting is not one of knowing. That experience 
alone can be termed 'knowing' in which we are convinced 



i 4 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

beyond the shadow of a doubt. 1 Thus our first test as to whether 
we are knowing or not at a particular moment is this one : the 
presence or absence of a feeling of conviction. Furthermore, 
the judge as to whether I now possess or do not possess this 
conviction is, of course, myself. I affirm that such and such an 
experience is a true instance of knowing, simply because I am 
convinced that it is so. In this matter the mind itself has the 
last word. We are not dealing for the moment with the more 
difficult question as to the demands that must be satisfied 
before the mind can attain to such conviction, for example, 
the demand for consistency and such like. We are merely 
pointing out the fact that knowing invariably involves a 
feeling of conviction, and that the presence or absence of 
the latter is indeed our first test of the presence or absence 
of knowledge. 

From the outset, therefore, we take it to be Mie, firstly, that 
knowing is a fact, and, secondly, that a characteristic mark of 
it is a sense of certainty. There is no knowing without a feeling 
of conviction. At this point, however, an important reservation 
must be made, namely, that a like feeling of conviction seems 
frequently to occur when actually we are not knowing. Con- 
sequently, it is in itself no infallible sign of knowledge. This 
greatly complicates our problem, for though admittedly there 
can be no knowing without conviction, there may yet (it would 
seem) be conviction without knowledge ; that is to say, we may 
feel sure that we are knowing at a time when actually, as we 
ourselves may be brought to confess later, we are not knowing. 2 

1 Incidentally, it is because this is so that one finds so much 
difficulty with the phrase 'knowing vaguely'. Knowing is such, we 
feel, that it leaves no room for vagueness. If an experience is marked 
by a sense of vagueness, then it is not knowledge, whatever else it be. 
It does not give conviction. 

a At present, however, we have no right to be dogmatic on this 
matter. For in spite of first appearances, the question may still be 
asked : Is our acquiescence in error absolutely identical in character 
with the conviction we feel when knowing, for instance, that two 
parallel straight lines will never meet? We must postpone the dis- 
cussion of this question. We shall return to it when considering 



INTRODUCTION 15 

If, on every such occasion, we really were knowing, there would 
be no difficulty in discovering any number of instances, but 
unfortunately we often believe we know when we do not. It is 
this fact of error which makes the problems of epistemology 
so desperately difficult. 

For, even at this early stage, we realize that knowing cannot 
involve error. That is to say, if in any experience we were 
convinced of something and thought ourselves to be actually 
knowing but later realized that we had been in error, we should 
not continue to think of the first experience as an instance of 
knowing. Consequently, in seeking for an example of knowing, 
it is not correct to accept as such any chance experience in which 
we find ourselves convinced of something. On the contrary, 
such an experience may easily fail to provide us with real 
knowledge, in spite of the fact that at the time we seem to be 
convinced that it does. And therefore we need to examine such 
instances carefully and not conclude too hurriedly that they 
are sound examples of knowing; we need to scrutinize our 
convictions and to hold our judgements in suspense that is to 
say, to become sceptical, though not with regard to knowing 
in general, since, as we have seen, such scepticism would make 
all advance impossible, but only with regard to these supposed 
instances of knowing. We must learn to stand aloof from them 
so as to examine them in as detached a manner as possible. 
And as we proceed with this examination, we may hope to gain 
greater insight into the nature of knowing itself. 

These considerations seem to necessitate a distinction which 
we propose to consider more fully at a later stage of the argu- 
ment. We must distinguish between a knowing, on the one hand, 
which, if it occur at all, is infallible, and a cognitive experience, 
on the other, which is definitely fallible. And this distinction 
is all the more necessary if we say that the cognitive experience 
may contain within it infallible knowing. Our cognitive experi- 
ences are fallible, yet they give us occasionally, we must believe, 

the character of error. On a prima facie view, however, it seems 
almost obvious that we feel just as certain about things when we err 
as when we actually do know. 



16 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

certain knowledge. But how can this be? How can man gain 
certainty when it is patent that his cognitive experiences as a 
whole are fallible ? In the third chapter of this work we shall 
face this difficulty and suggest a solution. But for the sake of 
clarity we recognize here, at the outset, the fallibility of our 
cognitive experiences even though we continue to demand an 
infallibility for knowing as such. 

But, again, if the state of knowing is one in which the knower 
is completely and absolutely convinced then we must also 
recognize from the very beginning of our inquiry the existence 
of a further mental state, which is still cognitive, but in which 
we are not fully convinced. It is convenient to term this state, 
one of opining, and in terming it so we adopt the practice of 
many earlier thinkers. We certainly possess the capacity to 
make a judgement whose truth is only probable, and we fre- 
quently find ourselves in the state of believing something 
without being quite certain about it. Were it to be shown false 
(though we hardly think it will) we should not be altogether 
unprepared. There are, of course, degrees of probability. 
Sometimes we put forward a statement in a very tentative 
manner expecting every moment to find evidence brought 
against it which will completely refute it. On other occasions, 
while w r e admit the absence of theoretical certainty, and while a 
measure of doubt still lingers in our minds, we should be very 
surprised, indeed, if our belief proved false. None the less, we 
are still opining. In both cases our state would be different 
from that in which we are completely convinced. This would 
have to be recognized even by those thinkers who confine 
human knowledge to probability and who deny that man ever 
can be completely convinced about anything. Indeed, their 
denial assumes the difference, and is not significant unless the 
assumption be made. But we, on the other hand, believe that 
the human mind does know with certainty, and it is this know- 
ing with certainty which provides the subject-matter for the 
present inquiry. Therefore, we shall not be directly concerned 
with the nature of opining in these pages. Nevertheless, it is as 
well to distinguish it from knowing at the very outset. 



INTRODUCTION 17 

Lastly, we may here add, no knowledge would ever be recog- 
nized by us to be such unless its object were the real. This 
assumption is so very obvious and trite that it seems hardly 
worthy of mention. At the same time, however, there might be, 
and indeed is, much disagreement as to the exact meaning and 
reference of the term 'real' in this context. 



THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 
i 

The Naive View 

WE are engaged upon the search for a fair and adequate example 
of knowing, and it might at first be thought that such an enter- 
prise need prove neither arduous nor protracted. For the naive 
person who has hardly begun to reflect about the nature of 
knowing can provide us with a ready example that appears 
perfectly satisfactory to him. I have only to open my eyes, he 
would say, to know. Seeing is knowing; so also are listening, 
smelling, tasting, and touching. I see this paper on which I now 
write, 1 hear the bird in the garden, I smell the rose which is 
before me, I touch the table and taste the fruit all such 
experiences are instances of knowing, and in searching for 
examples we need go no farther. Moreover, sense-perception, 
such a person might continue, is not merely one example but, 
clearly, the only possible example of knowledge, if we confine 
the latter term to the knowing of physical objects and of the 
world around us. For I can only come into contact with the 
external world through the senses. If I were blind, deaf, dumb, 
unable to taste and unable to touch, my state would be pitiable 
indeed ; not only because I lacked these capacities whilst other 
men possessed them, but even more because all knowledge 
would be denied me, excepting at most the vague 'inward* 
knowledge of my own feelings of pleasure and pain, of joy and 
sorrow if it were permissible to suppose that a creature in 
this unhappy condition could ever be capable of such emotions. 
This immense world in which I live would remain unknown to 
me in its entirety. I only begin to know it \<*hen I sense. The 
only outlet to the external world is the one afforded by sensation. 1 

1 The nai've person is, of course, no philosopher, and I have no 
philosophical school in mind. Furthermore, I doubt whether it 



20 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

Consequently, it would seem to him, if I deny that perceiving 
or sensing 1 is knowing, by that very act I also deny the possi- 
bility of any knowledge of the real world outside. And he never 
doubts that the real is what I see, touch, taste, and so on. Of 
course, I myself do not see all real things; there are many 
existences in this vast universe of being which I have not 
experienced, and which I am not likely to experience, but if I 
do ever come to a knowledge of them it will only be by way of 
the senses. Again, the sensing in question need not be mine, 
for I can learn by listening to, or reading about, the experiences 
of others in conditions completely different from mine. Know- 
ledge by hearsay is a very valuable means of widening one's 
spiritual horizon. But first-hand knowledge of the physical 
world whenever it occurs is, according to the naive person, 
invariably sense-perception. And as the latter thus tells us all 
we know about the external world it must bb as sound an 
example of knowing as is to be found anywhere. Hence an 
accurate description of sensing or perceiving would be an 
accurate description of knowing, and we need only carry it out 
to complete the task we have here set ourselves. 

The naive position, it must frankly be admitted, is not with- 
out its strength. It satisfies our first demand for conviction on 
the part of the knower, for there cannot be a greater degree of 
conviction than that possessed by the naive person. In sensing, 
he supposes, we experience the physical world exactly as it is, 
and each object as it is. In "all the choir of heaven and furniture 
of earth" there is nothing that remains hidden from me as a 
sentient being once I am in a position (spatially and tempor- 
ally) to sense it. At such a time reality lies open before me, 

would be at all fair to foister such crude views as these even upon 
the much maligned 'man in the street'. I have simply set forth 
explicitly for the purposes of the argument a position which is as 
such rarely held. Many apparently less crude reflections, however, 
when analysed are seen to originate with the implicit adoption of 
the above view, and it is the obvious position from which to start 
our present inquiry. 

1 For the naive person there is no distinction between the two 
terms. 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 21 

and I know it directly and completely without altering it in 
any way. 

But, what is it that provides the ground for such conviction ? 
Clearly the undeniable fact that all sense-experiences are, from 
one point of view, infallible. I look out through the window 
and see the blueness of the sky and the greyness of the house 
opposite. At the moment when this occurs, it is simply impos- 
sible to deny that I am seeing blue and grey. On this point 
scepticism can never arise. However long I reflect over the 
matter I can never bring myself to doubt that I am now seeing 
blue. Here surely is something about which I am completely 
convinced, for no greater degree of conviction can ever be 
possible; and here, the naive person would urge, is an excellent 
example of knowing. Furthermore, its excellence is the greater 
in that it gives complete certainty without involving me in any 
sustained intellectual effort, and is thus as valuable for its ease 
and spontaneity as for the conviction it inspires. 

In passing, its possession of these features is well illustrated 
by the readiness with which certain thinkers make use of 
seeing as a metaphor for the supreme kind of knowledge, some- 
times termed 'intuition'. The latter is the knowledge w T hich it 
is customary to attribute to God and to those higher spiritual 
beings who, like Him, do not proceed by way of laborious 
processes of reasoning but see all things directly and infallibly. 
"In heaven," it was well said by one such thinker, "each being 
is, as it were, an eye/' 1 Just as I cannot doubt that I am now 
seeing blue, so, too, I could not doubt this supreme knowledge 
if I possessed it; and, again, the ease with which I see blue is 
analogous to the ease with which I should know if I could 
'intuit' in this way. 2 Of course, this does not mean that such 
thinkers have ever supposed that seeing itself is in any way 
identical with such divine knowing, or even that seeing is 
actually a case of knowing. All we wish to point out is that the 



1 Plotinus, Ennead IV, iii. 18. ricei Ac . . . oiov 6(f>6a\iiu<; 

3 Most of the great philosophers have held that man also may 
possess this supreme knowledge, that such 'intuition* indeed is 
human knowledge par excellence. 



22 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

use of the metaphor would not be possible did not the thinkers 
who use it recognize in the sensory experience a certain 
infallibility and directness. 

Here, therefore, \ve contend, is the strength of the naive 
position. I am thoroughly convinced that 1 now see blue, and 
there is no room for doubt. If this were all that the position 
affirmed there could be no possible objection to it. Actually, 
however, the naive person is not content with so limited a 
statement. Not only do 1 see blue, but, he would add, I see the 
blue sky. Not only do I see red, but I see a red rose. My senses, 
it is true, give me colours, sounds, tastes, smells, and certain 
touch-feelings. Yet, the naive thinker would say, it is absurd 
to suppose that all they give is of such a nature. What I see now 
is this table with the books, papers, and vase which are on it. 
I see the man in the street, and hear the birds sing. My senses 
give me knowledge of physical objects as they are*; they open out 
before me the panorama of this actual world in which I exist. 
And such knowledge is as completely certain as is the seeing 
of blue, being identical \\ ith it since both are examples of sensing. 

Now, it is with regard to these additional claims that doubts 
arise on reflection. Just as the strength of the position lies in 
the presence of a certain infallibility in the sensory experience, 
so its weakness lies in a failure to point out carefully enough 
where the sensory experience is infallible and where it is fallible. 
For, actually, the view that the experience is an indubitable 
direct knowledge of the real physical world cannot hold its 
ground against the first breath of critical reflection that comes 
its w r ay. For, while I cannot doubt that I now see red, it is not 
impossible to doubt that I am seeing a red rose. On closer 
observation, for example, I may discover that what is before 
me is no real flower but only an artificial one, and that I was 
deceived at first in thinking it a real one. Or, again, I look across 
the Bristol Channel and see in the distance what appears to 
me to be land and what I take to be the Devon coast. But as I 
look, what I took to be land gradually moves away and I realize 
that I have been looking at a cloud. These examples are sufficient 
to cause us to doubt the infallibility of the sensory experience, 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 23 

as providing us with indubitable knowledge of the actual 
external world. Whether through the sensory experience we 
ever come to know anything about the physical world or not, 
it is clear that it does not invariably provide us with certain 
knowledge about it, and once we realize this the first naive 
position is no longer tenable. 1 

And this is true even though we now admit that there is 
room for a distinction within the whole sensory experience 
between a sensing and an act of judgement. 3 For as against the 
above examples it may be objected: "Your whole sensory 
experience of, for example, seeing a grey patch and mistaking 
it for the Devon coast is much broader than just the bare 
sensing. What you actually saw was a grey colour. There is no 
error in your seeing the grey ; the error entered when you tried 
to give greater significance to this grey patch by judging it to 
be the Devon coast. But if you had contented yourself with the 
affirmation 'I see grey' there could not possibly have been any 
error". 

Now if, for the moment, we granted such criticism to be 
sound, it still could not be used to bolster up the naive position 
in any way, for such criticism cannot have come from the 
mouth of the naive thinker; on the contrary, its occurrence is 
a definite sign that we are being forced away from that position 
and arc leaving it behind us. The naive person has no room 
for such distinctions; the possibility of our senses misleading 
us has never entered into his head; and the assertion that we 
see the colour grey and it alone would appear absurd to him. 
We shall suggest later that just seeing grey cannot in itself be 
held to be knowledge of the physical world, so that if such a 
person did accept the criticism made above he would be giving 

1 It, of course, remains none the less true that I do see the colour. 
It is also true that I know that I see it. The cognitive act of 'enjoying' 
my own experience is already present. But the naive person is inter- 
ested solely in my knowledge of the external world, and so disregards, 
as we shall do for the time being, this other element of knowing 
present in the sense-experience. 

3 The name then given to the whole experience as including both 
the sensing and the judging is usually 'perception*. 



24 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

up his fundamental tenet in its entirety, namely, that in sensing 
we know the actual physical world. This would signify, of 
course, a complete reversal of his former beliefs, and he would 
no longer represent the unreflective type first portrayed by us. 
But even if we suppose that seeing grey is actually an example 
of knowing the physical world that is, knowing a quality of 
(one part of) it the position of the critic is still very different 
from that of the naive person who affirms that sensing is a know- 
ing of the physical world in its fulness, and who certainly does 
not wish to limit that external physical world to a few colours, 
sounds, tastes, and the like. Whatever, therefore, we mean by 
'seeing grey', the criticism just put forward, if accepted by the 
cruder type of thinker, would seriously modify his former 
position, so much so that he could no longer be held to be a 
representative of the naive view. 

We see, then, that the confidence of the naive person in his 
belief is indeed justified to some extent by the presence of a 
certain infallibility in sensing: we shall reconsider this feature 
with more care in the third section of this chapter. On the other 
hand, we realize that the sensory experience is no infallible 
knowledge of the external world. For the testimony of the 
senses is often misleading, and never wholly trustworthy. And 
therefore, while we have not decided as yet in what way, if any, 
the sensory experience can be accepted as an example and type 
of knowing, we feel that the claims made for it by the naive 
person are invalid. It is no easy, infallible, and exact knowledge 
of the world around us, as the slightest reflection will show. 
On the contrary, the deceptiveness of the senses compels us 
to reject the naive position as totally inadequate and to demand 
a more critical account of sensation. It is to this consideration 
that we now turn. 

2 

Critical Theories 

In the previous section the fallacious character of the naive 
position has been made clear. It is crude, over-simple, and 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 25 

completely untenable. Dissatisfaction with it has found outlet 
in many and varied critical theories of perception, but it is not 
our purpose to set out in detail the history of these theories. 
Such an historical account lies beyond the scope of the present 
work, though it will be foolish not to make whatever use we 
can of the lessons learnt by past philosophers in our own efforts 
at describing knowledge as adequately as possible. Sufficient 
use, however, will be made of earlier thought if, guided by it, 
we lay bare the basis common to all the many criticisms of the 
naive position, and if, following the same guidance, we proceed 
to discover for ourselves the soundest critical standpoint with 
regard to the nature of perception. Our problem, therefore, 
may be set forth thus: Can we, rejecting the naive position, 
continue to term perception an instance of knowing, and, if 
we do so, will the term 'knowing' retain exactly the same 
meaning in the* new speculations as it did in those of a cruder 
kind? 

All critical theories of perception start from the realization 
of the occasional deceptiveness of the senses. The view that 
the sensory experience provides us with an infallible and exact 
knowledge of physical objects in the external world is thoroughly 
fallacious. In the example given earlier I affirmed that I saw 
the Devon coast. Later I was myself forced to the conclusion 
that the affirmation was erroneous, and that my senses had 
misled me. This possibility of error, as w r e pointed out previ- 
ously, is sufficient of itself to demonstrate, once and for all, 
that perception is no infallible knowledge of the world around 
us, and that the position of the naive thinker, in spite of his 
conviction and dogmatic assurance, is wholly untenable. 

But how did it come about that my senses, on this occasion, 
misled me, and what exactly do I mean when making that 
assertion? In this respect an objection arose in the first section 
which, while illustrating the beginnings of the new critical 
reflection, throws much light also on the source of error in 
sensing. Actually, it was objected, I did not see the Devon 
coast. I only saw the colour grey, or speaking still more 
accurately a grey patch. Now the error in the whole sensory 



26 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

experience described as seeing the Devon coast arose not in 
the seeing of the grey patch, but in the judgement which 
immediately followed upon the seeing. Given the grey patch, 
I endeavoured to discover its significance, and judged it to 
be the Devon coast, on the ground of, for example, its similarity 
to a grey patch which I had often seen before in that direction 
and which I had invariably taken for the Devon coast. And it 
was in this effort to discover the significance of the 'given' that 
I fell into error. 

There is here a clear distinction between a seeing and a 
judging within the whole sensory experience of seeing the 
Devon coast. We are not usually cognizant of any such dis- 
tinction when we actually experience the sensation, for what 
we have called the judging requires so little effort on our part, 
on account of the very numerous occasions upon which we 
have made like judgements, that we are hardly *ware of it until 
we are compelled, by some means or other, to focus our atten- 
tion upon it. But this distinction, once realized, makes possible 
a better understanding of what occurs when, as we say, our 
senses mislead us. The error in sensing now reveals itself to 
be a case of false judgement ; we affirm something to be that 
which it is not. Hence, as the result of this first rough analysis 
of the whole sensory experience, we may now more clearly 
understand why it cannot possibly provide us with infallible 
knowledge. Any and every sensory experience of the kind 
illustrated in the above example, we now argue, involves an 
act of judgement; it is not mere sensing, it is perceiving; and, 
as human judgement is fallible, it follows that the sensory 
experience taken as a concrete whole cannot be infallible. 
That is to say, being misled by sensing means, in this case, 
making an erroneous judgement, which is part of the whole 
sensory experience. 

Thus, when once the distinction between mere sensing and 
judging is set up within the whole sensory experience the 
occasional error we discover must be attributed not to the 
sensing but to the judging. It might seem to follow from this 
that whereas in the judging we sometimes know and sometimes 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 27 

err, in the mere sensing we never err but always know if we 
are agreed that 'knowing' is the correct term for seeing grey, 
for example. But here a difficulty ensues. If the mere sensing 
is itself knowing, what necessity can there be for this additional 
judgement ? Why should we go out of our way to involve ourselves 
in judgements which are frequently erroneous if we already know ? 

The answer can only be that, whatever we do know by mere 
sensing (if we know anything), we do not know all we wish to 
know; we are left with a gap in our knowledge which sensing 
cannot fill. Consequently, we have recourse to judging. For 
though we were for the moment to grant that the mere sensing 
does give knowledge, it clearly does not give that full and 
complete knowledge of the physical world which alone would 
satisfy us. If it did, of course, judging within the sensory 
experience would be wholly unnecessary. We should know by 
mere sensing ail that we chose to know. The opposite, how- 
ever, is clearly the case. Mere sensing, it would seem, simply 
provides us at most with information which is not itself full 
and exact knowledge of things as they arc, but is rather a help 
of some sort towards the attainment of that fuller and exacter 
knowledge. If we take it to be full knowledge we deceive 
ourselves. At most, it is only a beginning needing the aid of 
further mental operations before an exact knowledge of the 
object can occur. 

On this point all critics of the naive view are agreed. Here 
their theories find a common starting-point, however much 
they may diverge later. Thus the critical view which most nearly 
resembles the naive position avoids the latter's naivete by 
seriously modifying the claims made for sensing. In sensing, 
it asserts, we do not know the full physical world, nor indeed 
do we know any one particular existent as it really is. Sensation 
(that is, sensing) merely provides us with knowledge of certain 
features or qualities of existents. This knowledge, however, is 
exact, direct, and infallible in character; but it is not complete 
knowledge of the real. There must also be other capacities and 
faculties at work. In sensing I only know that this apple before 
me is red in colour, sweet, smooth, hard, and has a peculiar 



28 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

smell of its own. That it is one, a unity, that it is a body, or, 
again, that it is like another apple, and comparable with it these 
things I know not through sensation but through some other 
means. Therefore in gaining a knowledge of the one physical 
object I do not merely sense it, for sensing gives me knowledge 
only of its 'sensory' qualities, as instanced above, but I must 
also set those other faculties to work in order to know all its 
qualities and relations. Thus my final complete knowledge 
of the object can only be the outcome of a combination or syn- 
thesis of many features known by many faculties into one whole. 1 
At this juncture we do not wish to discuss the general theory 
of knowledge implied in this first type of criticism. Our interest 
at present is confined to the problem of sense-experience. And 
since this is so we need only attend to the following considera- 
tions. The adherents of this first critical position have to pre- 
suppose that, if knowledge of the whole physioal object is ever 
to be possible, then the knowledge we get of the 'sensory' 
features in sensing must be certain and infallible, since we 
depend upon it solely for knowledge of these features, in such a 
way that if it gave us error we should never be able to recognize 
it as error. We must take what the senses 'give' with respect 
to such features, and if they do not give the truth that is, if 
they do not reveal the real features of real things then, however 
true our knowledge of the other features may be, the final whole 
that we make by combining the different features will necessarily 
be false. It is, consequently, essential for this view that sensing 
should give indubitable knowledge of the particular features 
in question, for with regard to them there is no appeal beyond 
the senses. I do not see (by bare seeing) the rose itself in so 
far the view rejects the na'ive theory but I do see its redness, 
and thus know finally and absolutely this real quality pertaining 
to the real existence. 

1 This act of combination may, however, occur spontaneously, 
being, indeed, not so much a combining on the part of the mind, 
it might be said, but rather the apprehension of the qualities as 
being in combination. (Even so, the position is clearly a difficult one 
to defend.) 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 29 

But just as it could not be granted that sensing provides us 
with exact knowledge of physical objects, so now the claim that 
it invariably provides exact knowledge of a real feature of the 
physical object must also be held invalid. Error seems to be 
possible even when we merely affirm that a certain physical 
object has this or that colour. For instance, I may look at a 
wall and say, "This wall is red". On the view under considera- 
tion, though the seeing gives me no other knowledge of this 
object, it yet does convince me beyond the possibility of doubt 
that the colour of the wall is red. But if, now, following some 
pre-arranged signal, a friend looks at the wall at the same 
moment as myself, but a great distance off, he will probably see 
it to be grey, and will have to say, "That wall is grey", A third 
person looking through a powerful microscope upon some 
portion of the wall will simultaneously see it to be, perhaps, 
brown, and will say, "This wall is really brown", and there will 
be as much evidence to justify his assertion as there is to justify 
mine, or that of my friend. Now, in point of fact, the wall can- 
not itself be red, grey, and brown at one and the same time. It 
is quite true that, as the thinkers who hold this view would 
speedily contend, the difference in what we see is due to a 
difference in the circumstances in which we see. But, even so, 
it is clear that seeing is not invariably an exact knowing of the 
colour of a thing. If the wall is red, then when seen as grey or 
brown its real colour is not being known. Consequently, seeing 
a colour is not always the direct knowledge of a real feature of 
an external thing as this particular theory would claim. 

"But", it may be objected, "you are causing unnecessary 
confusion. In every case of sensing the 'given* has to be 
'adjusted'. In this instance we must 'adjust' by allowing for 
the differences in the circumstances of the three persons when 
seeing. Once this allowance is made, the real colour of the object 
can then be determined with ease." Now, if we adopt this 
position, then clearly what I see is, on occasion at least, no ex- 
ternal existence, nor even a quality of an external existence, but 
rather something which may provide me with a clue to know- 
ledge of the external existence a very different theory. Seeing 



3 o THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

itself, we should then be admitting, does not always give direct 
knowledge even of a feature of the physical thing. Furthermore, 
once I begin to 'adjust', my conviction that I know the real 
colour of the thing depends not on the seeing of the colour, 
but on the 'adjusting'. I should say, then, that I know that this 
wall is red, not so much because I see it to be red (for I know 
that in other circumstances I may see it to be grey or brown), 
but because in normal conditions I see it to be red. My con- 
viction is based not on the fact that I saw red, but on the con- 
clusion to which I have come, as a result of a process of reason- 
ing, that conditions were in that case normal (and abnormal if 
I saw grey or brown). If then we do know in such a case, the 
knowledge, even of this one feature of the real, does not occur 
by way of mere sensing that is, in this case, by merely seeing a 
colour. More is present. Seeing a colour in itself does not 
provide me with certain knowledge of physical objects. Con- 
sequently, this first critical position, we are led to conclude, 
is no more tenable on reflection than is the naive position, for 
it cannot rightly be granted that we know, in sensation, directly 
and exactly, even a feature or quality of an externally existing 
thing. 

But if now what we see is neither the real physical object 
nor a quality of it, what else can it be, and how can it aid us 
to know the real ? An answer is provided by the second main 
critical position, which holds that sensing presents us with a 
content illustrative of the real independent of us while not 
itself being that independently real. We are provided with 
'sensa' which are related in some way to the external existences, 
while yet not revealing them as they are. By working on such 
content, however, adjusting, relating, classifying, and so on, 
we may hope in time to gain adequate knowledge of the inde- 
pendently real itself. This position is, we believe, in essentials 
one with the famous Theory of Representative Perception, 
which produced so much bewilderment in the minds of six- 
teenth-, seventeenth-, and eighteenth-century thinkers. That 
theory, however, was sometimes expressed in a cruder and 
more naive fashion. The ideas in the mind, the mind's imme- 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 31 

ttiate objects, were conceived as exact copies of the real ; though, 
indeed, most thinkers soon realized that the 'ideas' of secondary 
qualities, colours, tastes, sounds, and the like were not exact 
copies, but only represented in a vague way certain 'powers 1 
in things, one of which, for example, caused me to see a particu- 
lar colour. The still more critical position now being put forward, 
however, holds that none of these 'ideas' or 'sensa' are exact 
copies, but simply that they are sufficiently representative to 
guide me to the real. We cannot say, without being naive, that 
sensing is itself a knowing of the externally real ; but we can 
say that it provides us with a content which inexactly copies the 
real, and that if by a process of thinking the inexactitude of the 
copy could be determined it would be an easy task to correct 
the copy where necessary, so that knowledge of the real might 
ensue. The basis of this view, however, is identical with that 
of the Theory of Representative Perception; namely, that in 
sensation we have to deal in the first place with representations 
of the independently real and not with that real itself. 

Once we have arrived at this stage a distinction of very great 
importance becomes possible and, indeed, necessary. This is 
the distinction between what is and what appears, between 
reality and appearance, between the actual existence and the 
idea or image. In sensing we do not experience the real as it is, 
but an appearance of it. The content given by sensation, accord- 
ing to the new critical theory, is phenomenal or what appears 
only. We have to seek with its aid for the independently real. 
But if this be taken to mean that we are to search amongst the 
representations for that one which images the external with 
sufficient exactitude to give us knowledge of it, a serious 
difficulty immediately arises. For how can we ever know whether 
a representation or copy of X is a good one or not unless we 
have known X itself? Now on the theory under consideration 
we sense only the representations or copies and never the 
originals; it is, therefore, impossible to test these copies, since 
we cannot finally test a copy's worth except by the original. 
This is an old criticism, but none the less sound; for, so long 
as we continue to think of the problem in terms of copy and 



32 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

original, then without a knowledge of the original we cannot 
know whether a representation does adequately represent what 
it is supposed to represent or whether, on the contrary, the 
representation is false. If I say that what I see is appearance 
only, then when I see the colour of a wall to he red, grey, and 
brown in different circumstances I must be able to see the real 
colour itself before I can say which of those appearances red 
wall, grey wall, or brown wall, is the truest copy. Yet colour as 
an actual property of a real external existent if there be real 
colour in this sense is just what, according to this theory, I 
cannot see. 

Against any theory, therefore, which holds that the imme- 
diate object of sensation is a representation, and that we only 
know the real object when we have discovered that one repre- 
sentation among the many 'given' which exactly represents it, 
the following criticism may be urged. Never,by any process, 
can we learn the degree of exactitude with which such repre- 
sentations mirror the external world beyond the representations 
if they do mirror it at all unless we succeed in directly 
apprehending that external world itself. Yet such direct appre- 
hension is, on this view, impossible by way of sensing. While 
if another approach to the external real were posited providing 
us directly with perfect knowledge of the real object, then the 
search within the content of sensation for the best copy would 
be wholly unnecessary. The dilemma in this case is real enough. 
For if such direct access to the external is indeed possible, then 
the representations of sense are superfluous; they are copies 
(most often inexact copies) of what we already know directly. 
But if, on the other hand, we refuse to admit the actuality of 
such direct knowledge, we then can never test the copies in the 
light of the original and so can never discover the true copy. Such 
a dilemma shows the unsatisfactory nature of this theory and 
necessitates its rejection. Knowing cannot be a search for the 
best copy of the real amongst the many representations provided 
in sensation. Here, again, is a view which a little reflection 
shows to be completely untenable. 

It is consequently characteristic of those philosophers who 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 33 

attempt a new approach to this question, by which they hope 
to overcome the difficulties of Representative Perception and 
like theories, that they seek no longer to discover in the 'given' 
of sense representations which adequately mirror the external 
real. On the contrary, they try to discover truths which are 
true simply because they carry with them a validity that is 
necessary. They try to find within their sensory experiences 
what must be, what is so necessary that it cannot be denied. 
And it is this act of discovery which they term knowing. They 
no longer expressly seek for the external 'represented' in sense- 
data, but for the inevitable, whether it be external or not. This 
profound difference in attitude between what we have termed 
the second main critical standpoint and the third, which we are 
now beginning to consider, must be fully realized and con- 
stantly borne in mind if we would understand some further 
developments ijjt epistemology. A sensory experience taken 
as a whole is to be conceived as revealing truths only in so far 
as there is within it a knowing of the necessarily valid. The 
knowing involved in the sensory experience is simply the 
discovery of those truths which hold necessarily within the 
content of sense-experience. 

Now if we are to know the inevitable in the 'given' of sense 
we shall succeed in doing so only as we lay bare inevitable 
relations. For, clearly, what we know in this case must be 
relations which hold universally within the appearances pre- 
sented by sense. And I judge them to be inevitable because I 
know them to be universal. Consequently, to say that I know 
the necessarily valid, or what must be, simply means that I 
know a law or laws which a particular set of experiences must 
always obey. Knowing, indeed, on this view, is no longer to 
be conceived as the apprehension of one particular physical 
object in its particularity, whether directly or indirectly by 
way of representations ; it is rather the realization of a definite 
law as a fact in a particular experience, which law is the 'truth' 
of that experience. And this new meaning of truth makes it 
wholly unnecessary for us who desire true knowledge to seek 
in our sensory experience for representations of external reals. 



34 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

But at this stage an additional consideration of very great 
importance must be brought forward. We still conceive the 
'given* of sense as 'appearance', as only partially real in a vague 
way which at present we do not understand. We also continue 
to admit the existence of an independently real which, we 
suppose, somehow or other produces in us sensations, though 
sensing gives us no knowledge of that real. Consequently, the 
law known in the sensory experience does not hold of this 
independently real world; it only holds of the phenomenal 
sphere. Now a law holding among external real things is on 
the face of it wholly independent of the mind knowing it, 
and if I ever know it I shall only do so by apprehending it 
directly as it really is. But, clearly, a law known in the pheno- 
menal world need not be thus independent. It is not a real law 
of real things. To say so would be to revert at this crucial 
moment in the argument to the naive position, without being 
able in any way to justify the reversal. On the contrary, the law 
I know in the phenomenal world is itself phenomenal. It is no 
law of really existing things, but is at least as dependent upon 
the mind that knows it as is the phenomenal of which it holds. 

A further consideration, however, may now show that 
actually such laws are even less independent of the mind than 
is the manifold 'given 1 in sensation. For while the law, to know 
which is to apprehend the necessarily valid in our experience, 
holds of and in a phenomenal world, yet it itself is not 'given' 
with the phenomena in sense-experience. What are 'given' are 
colours, sounds, tastes, smells, feelings of resistance, of smooth- 
ness, of roughness. But, for instance, that one 'appearance' is 
produced by another as effect by cause is never 'given'. I have 
never seen, heard, smelt, tasted, nor touched such a relation. 
We never sense any definite connection within the manifold 
presented by sense, though we know many such connections. 
To take another example ; by just seeing a deep yellow, or, if 
it be preferred, a yellow patch, I cannot see its connection with 
the sweetness of an orange, I am only 'given' the colour yellow, 
though I immediately think of sweetness. These connections 
then are never 'given' with the content of the phenomenal 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 35 

world; they are not 'presented' in our sense-experience; so 
that they do not appear to possess even that meagre measure 
of independence of the mind which phenomena still possess 
in that they are 'given' to the mind rather than created by it. 

Therefore, according to the present view, we do not know 
the 'truth' about phenomena that is to say, their laws and 
their necessary order (the existence of which in the phenomenal 
world enables us to predict certain events as inevitable) by 
simply apprehending such laws in the way in which a naive 
person would say we 'apprehend' the real. Nor, again, are they 
'given' in the content of our sense-experience, as colours and 
sounds are 'given'. Only one alternative, consequently, remains: 
namely, that the source of such laws is inward, that we, ourselves 
create out of our experience an ordered whole in which we may 
justifiably expect certain things to happen, since we who thus 
expect phenomena to follow laws have ourselves set down the 
laws they have to follow. If we are to speak consistently and 
significantly, bearing in mind all that has been said up to the 
present about the nature of the sensory content, then it is thus 
alone that knowledge of the necessarily valid can occur, and 
only thus can we explain our possession of ordered systems 
of such knowledge in the various sciences. But it also follows, 
if this be the true account, that human knowledge is not of the 
real world itself, 1 since all we have to deal with is the pheno- 
menal, and this alone is the content of our experience. Sensation 
never 'gives' us the real, though what it 'gives' is somehow 
remotely connected with the real. Therefore, if we, who have 
only the 'given' of sense to work upon, desire knowledge, it 
can only be knowledge of an ordered phenomenal world, 
wherein the order itself is neither 'grasped' nor 'given', but 
introduced into the 'given' by the mind itself. That the 'given' 
should in this way allow itself to be ordered by mind is cer- 
tainly strange enough, for, though phenomenal, it is still in a 
measure independent of the mind. Nevertheless, this must be 
the case if human knowledge is ever to be possible. While, 
indeed, the fact that the phenomenal is still, in however slight 
1 That is, 'real* as opposed to 'phenomenal'. 



36 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

a measure, independent of the knowing mind must be reckoned 
a very fortunate one for us, since it gives our science a faint 
external reference which saves it from complete subjectivity. 

This position 1 certainly avoids the central fallacy of the 
Theory of Representative Perception ; we no longer seek the 
best representations or copies of we-know-not-what originals 
a task of Sisyphus. But it avoids it at a price that few would be 
prepared to pay who fully understood the implications of the 
new theory as it stands. For by it the human mind is adjudged 
incapable of ever coming to kno\v the real external world. 
Instead, we are shut up within a world of appearances, vaguely 
suspecting the existence of a real world which has produced 
and is producing these experiences within our consciousness, 
but which is nevertheless unknown to us and unknowable. 
Prisoners within the confines of the phenomenal, the urge 
for knowledge which possesses us can receive 'only such satis- 
faction as comes from knowing this shadow-world of appear- 
ances ; nor is there anywhere a path that can lead us to the real 
world beyond. 

In spite, therefore, of the necessity which permeates this 
limited sphere, making human prediction possible, and in spite 
of the 'objectivity', as being equal to necessity and universality, 
which has thus been assured us, we cannot rest satisfied with 
this position. However certain our knowledge be, if we are 
quite explicitly conscious of the fact that it only applies to the 
semi-real world of phenomena, then it cannot be an example of 
that perfect knowledge for which we seek. Indeed, using words 
significantly, we do not feel justified in terming this creation of 
a systematic world of phenomena (which we know to be pheno- 
mena and nothing more) 'knowing' at all. On the contrary, 
our awareness in this instance of the fact that we are confined 
and limited, that what is before us is the phenomenal and half- 

1 The position we have in mind, of course, is the Kantian. We do 
not put the argument forward in an historical form, however, because 
we do not wish to argue as to whether Kant did hold this view or 
did not. Our attitude throughout this essay is different. Here is a 
view, whoever first put it forward. Is it itself sound? 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 37 

real only, would approach nearer to our ideal of knowledge, 
for it would actually be a knowledge of what really is. Although, 
incidentally, such knowing would remain \vholly unexplained 
and inexplicable on the theory under consideration. For human 
knowing, according to the latter, is more akin in nature to the 
dream and to the fantasy than to knowledge of the real, though 
it be a dream that greatly helps us in our dealings with the 
'appearances' of everyday life. To accept the position as it 
stands would be to accept an intolerable bondage; we should 
lose all confidence in the mind's power to know; we should be 
plunged into a state of hopeless and despairing scepticism. 
How could it be otherwise if we knew beforehand that the 
object of human knowledge must invariably be phenomenal in 
nature ? 

As a consequence a further development of the argument 
becomes inevitable if only to help us regain our faith in ourselves 
as beings capable of real knowledge. For the new theory that 
now emerges re-establishes in philosophical speculation the 
common-sense conviction that what we know /.v, that the real 
is the knowable, and not, as with the earlier theory, an unknow- 
able. The new development, however, is no fresh start. It 
re-endorses earlier criticism and makes them its basis. For it 
the 'given' of sense is appearance only; there can be no return 
to the naive position. Secondly, a 'true' object cannot be found 
by searching for exact representations of the real in the content 
of our sense-experience; consequently, the Theory of Repre- 
sentative Perception and any other theory that approximates 
to it must be rejected. Thirdly, the 'principles' whereby the 
'given' is ordered are not themselves 'given' but are ways in 
which the mind thinks appearances. In a word, the new theory 
is faced with this difficult task: it must confirm such prior 
criticism, while, at the same time, it must free the human 
mind from the limitations which those very criticisms have 
seemingly shown to be necessary. 

It carries out this act of emancipation, to its own satisfaction 
at least, by adding one more criticism in its turn to those 
already made. For it asserts that the theory we have just been 



38 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

discussing fails lamentably in one respect. Though certainly 
revolutionary in many of the changes it introduces, nevertheless, 
as the result of too close an allegiance to the past, the theory 
misses the real and vital consequence of its own position. A 
complete break away from the earlier standpoint, which, 
emphasized the reality of an external thing-in-itself , is necessary 
on the lines already set down for us by the theory just discussed. 
That the latter, however, failed to carry out completely this 
revolution in thought is proved up to the hilt by the phenomen- 
alistic nature of its epistemology. 

Yet it securely established the grounds for this further 
advance. For once the three criticisms set forth above have 
been admitted, then surely one cannot long continue in the 
belief that the 'appearances' of sense in any way point to an 
external real, and that the only real knowledge would be the 
apprehension of this thing-in-itself outside, although actually 
such an apprehension is wholly impossible for us. For if the 
real is what lies outside, influencing us in our sensing, but yet 
unknown to us as sensing, and if again no other point of con- 
tact with that real is possible for the human mind, then no 
amount of 'adjusting' and no measure of intellectual labour 
can lead us to knowledge of the real. Indeed, all such working 
upon the 'given' of sense would lead us directly away from 
rather than towards the real, since ex hypothesi our nearest 
approach to reality occurs in sensing itself. And worst con- 
sequence of all if we persist in this view a most confusing 
distinction between the real and the true must be made. The 
'real', as such, it will be necessary to assert, belongs to a sphere 
which is transcendent and cannot be experienced by us; the 
true, however, is the necessarily valid within the world of our 
experience. Hence the paradoxical position, that we may gain 
truth while still remaining wholly ignorant of the real. 

But all these disquieting consequences, it is now pointed out, 
are due to the simple fact that we persist unnecessarily in the 
belief that the real is this thing-in-itself, this existence that 
transcends human experience. If we take our experience as it 
is and forget for the time being all the various theories whereby 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 39 

we have tried to interpret it, there is nothing, the new view holds, 
that makes this concept of the transcendent necessary ; nothing 
that makes it impossible for us to hold that reality is more 
apparent in thinking than in sensing, that our 'true' object 
(which indeed is not so much found in appearance itself, 
but is rather the thought-out 'truth* of such appearance in the 
sense we have already explained) is itself what really exists, 
that, lastly, the principles of the understanding are capable 
of ordering not only the phenomena of sense, but the real world 
of actual existence. There is, as we say, nothing that makes 
impossible such a belief if we once free ourselves from the 
tyranny of earlier thinking. 

Certainly, such a theory of knowledge involves a radical 
change of outlook that makes the whole universe of being appear 
in a new and perhaps at first strange light. For if the mind's 
principles are fche laws of what really exists, and not only of 
a world of phenomena, such complete accord between mind- 
created truth and the real must mean that the real itself is 
spiritual in nature in this sense, at least, that mind provides 
the ultimate explanation of its being. That is to say, actual 
existence in all its forms must be identical in its ultimate nature 
with this mind of ours, otherwise we could never by working 
upon the manifold provided in sensing, under the guidance of 
the principles of the understanding, hope to gain for ourselves 
ii complete knowledge of the real world, nor could we account 
for the fact that the necessarily valid is the real. All this may 
appear strange, but if the facts be otherwise, then, according 
to the present theory, it can only mean that the real is not 
rational and so cannot be known by us, and we are plunged 
again into the scepticism which we are trying to avoid. We are 
forced, nolentes volentes, either to deny that human beings ever 
can possess real knowledge or to assert as our one way of escape 
that the real is spiritual and that, therefore, our thinking can 
legislate for it. The real conforms to those principles which 
my own thinking sets forward as true; so that the mind can 
construct truth, not of itself creating the world which it knows, 
for that world is already created, but rethinking the very 



40 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

thoughts which created it. It follows that in the seeing of colours, 
the hearing of sounds, and in all those experiences which we 
term sensations we are at the stage of Appearance, wherein the 
mind's knowledge of the real is vague and indistinct, but that 
this knowledge becomes more and more adequate and com- 
prehensive as we proceed to discover by thought, guided by its 
laws or principles, the inmost 'truth' of what appears. 

Therefore we needs must reject the 'sensationalist' pre- 
suppositions of the former position. If knowledge is to be in 
any way possible, what is real is not something outside affecting 
us in sensation whilst yet remaining unknown. For the con- 
sequence of such a view is that we find ourselves compelled 
to turn away from the real, since we know beforehand that it 
is utterly impossible for our finite minds to 'get out' to it. As a 
result we are confined, against our will, within the limits of a 
world of appearances, which we do our best to order as well as 
we can. But if real knowledge is ever to be possible, we must 
deny this conception of a transcendent external world and 
free ourselves from the bogey of the merely phenomenal. We 
must assert that the real itself lies 'inward' and not 'outward'; 
that, indeed, the distinction between 'outward' and 'inward' 
loses its meaning: that the mind can order and legislate for 
the real because reality itself is spiritual in nature: that if we 
seek the essence of anything, what it exactly and most truly 
is, we shall discover that it is something spiritual: and that, 
finally, this something is better known by conceiving and 
thinking than by sensing. 

This, then, is no idle and fantastic theory. On the contrary, 
it is the position to which we are driven by the logic of the 
argument. It is the inevitable conclusion of a trend of thought 
that begins with the rejection of the naive view set forth in the 
first section. At present we do not mean to discuss the soundness 
of this final position (that is to say, of an Hegelian type of Ideal- 
ism) as a whole system of philosophy. Our more immediate 
concern is the problem of sense-experience. And from this 
point of view, what follows asserts an obvious truth: If it be 
said, criticizing the first naive view, that the content of the 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 41 

jensory experience cannot be the real as it is, but must rather 
DC thought of as some partial presentation of the real, then, if 
consistently worked out, the argument proceeding from such 
a starting-point must lead us step by step either to a thorough- 
going scepticism or to this spiritually realistic theory of being 
and of knowledge which we have just been expounding. Reality, 
we must say, if we wish to avoid scepticism, is not some- 
thing, to be looked for outside mind, but something through 
and through 'mental', 'ideal', or, again, 'spiritual* in its 
character. 1 

We believe it possible, therefore, to draw the following 
important conclusion. If we assert that sensation is the only 
outlet to the real, and that what is 'given' in sensation is appear- 
ance, even though we add that such an appearance is the real- 
as-appearing, or the physical-as-appearing, or, again, the actual- 
as-appearing, rrfeaning thereby something which only just fails 
to be the real or the physical or the actual itself, and if we thus 
base our criticism upon the distinction between appearance 
and reality, then inevitably we are closed up within a phenomenal 
world, however much we long for the noumenal. And, unless 
we succeed in finding the noumenal by holding that the real 
is spiritual in its ultimate nature, we shall have cut ourselves 
off for ever from the real. So long as Appearance and Reality 
is thus the predominating antithesis in men's minds when the 
attempt is made to give an adequate account of knowledge, so 
long also must the Idealist interpretation of knowledge and of 
its object of necessity ensue to save mankind from the deepest 
and the most despairing forms of scepticism. Such is the con- 
clusion which we believe to be fully warranted by the inquiry 
carried out by us in this section. 

1 It may be objected that a third alternative is possible, namely, 
that we can 'infer' the nature of the external real from the pheno- 
menal. But if what is 'presented* is phenomenal containing no clue 
or hint as to the true nature of the external real, it would seem 
logically impossible to 'infer' the real. Where such inference occurs 
it must be because we already know something of the nature of that 
external real for example, that it coheres. We shall endeavour to 
show later how this knowledge comes about* 



42 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

3 
A Further Critical Position 

The Idealist position at which we have now arrived 
confirms our faith in our cognitive powers and dispels our 
scepticism. It also frees us from the insufferable bondage of 
phenomenalism. It assures us that the real itself can be known 
by mind. But the fully real, it would say, is not known by all 
minds, since some minds are less developed than others. For 
instance, the mind which puts its trust in perception is confused 
in its knowledge. Perception is a low stage of experience at 
which the content experienced is only half true. It is the stage 
of Appearance, illusory and deceptive. But a rational being 
cannot and, Idealism adds, need not remain at this stage. 
Within the content experienced in perception there are germs 
of a fuller truth and the mind of its own power, working 
according to its own principles, can develop them, constructing 
(or reconstructing) by this development the real itself. For 
as thus developed what appears loses its illusory character. 
The half-real becomes more completely real. Appearance is 
becoming Reality. If the shadow- realm of Appearance be likened 
to a prison, it is a prison within which the prisoner is not 
confined against his will. Its doors are open wide to any being 
whom Reason has taught to walk. 

Are we then to adopt the Idealist solution as here set forth ? 
One point has already been made clear. The moment we feel 
compelled to assert in a critical mood that in the sensory 
experience what we gain is wholly phenomenal in character, 
then we have, ultimately, only two alternatives from which to 
choose, either complete scepticism as to the knowledge of the 
real, on the one hand, or Idealism, on the other. And while, no 
doubt, many thinkers consider that the assumptions made by 
the Idealist are so unjustified as to vitiate his solution of the 
problem, so that it cannot really be considered as an alternative, 
yet no serious inquirer after the truth ever delights in scepticism 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 43 

as such, nor will he adopt it while there is any other satisfactory 
solution at hand. Hence the strength of the case for an Idealism. 

Nevertheless, in spite of its strength, we do not intend to 
adopt the Idealist solution in this essay; and we must now try 
to show why. We do not adopt the solution because we feel 
that the problem which Idealism thus attempts to solve is an 
unreal one. It arises from misapprehension and faulty analysis. 
For we suspect that the whole difficulty consequent upon the 
adoption of phenomenalism ought to have been avoided at the 
outset. As yet, we suggest, full justice has not been done by us 
to the facts of the sensory experience. And in this section we 
propose to begin criticizing the naive position afresh. We hope 
to show that, actually, the facts when rightly examined do not 
drive us into phenomenalism, and that the validity of the whole 
antithesis between Appearance and Reality as set forth in the 
last section is fo be questioned. And if it can be shown that 
phenomenalism is unnecessary, and even unjustifiable, then 
surely the Idealist solution, which is to save us from the evil 
consequences of phenomenalism, is in so far equally unneces- 
sary. There may, of course, be other powerful arguments for 
Idealism. We are here attempting no refutation of Idealism in 
general. But if the \vhole phenomenalist position is shown to be 
the outcome of insufficient attention to the evidence available, 
and if on paying greater attention to this evidence the difficul- 
ties and problems of phenomenalism vanish with it itself, then 
clearly the need for an adoption of Idealism on our part as a 
solution of such difficulties no longer exists. 

Now we assumed throughout the last section that bare sen- 
sation that is to say, the seeing of colours, hearing of sounds, 
and so on has always some cognitive value. 1 The fact that the 
assumption was made so readily (and, in a sense, so unwittingly) 

1 It ought to bo emphasized, perhaps, that we mean by 'sensation' 
the mere hearing a sound, tasting a taste, seeing a colour, and not 
the whole sensory experience, as it occurs, for instance, in the adult 
human mind. The bare hearing of a sound no doubt is only a part 
of the whole auditory experience. But by a process of analysis and 
abstraction we shall consider this element in itself in order to show 
that it itself is not knowledge. 



44 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

by us suggests that we were still under the spell of the first 
naive view, which looks upon sensation as exact and perfect 
knowledge of the real. And because we made this assumption 
then doubt about the cognitive character of sensation was not 
carried to the extremes that certain considerations would seem 
to demand. We have throughout presupposed that sensing is a 
form of knowing. In the last section, certainly, it was, granted 
that the knowledge given was very vague; indeed, the word 
'appearance' was used in order to suggest the distressing 
obscurity that characterized the content of sensory knowledge. 
But yet we never doubted that sensation did provide us with 
knowledge, however indistinct and inadequate. We must no 
longer, however, withhold our minds from this supreme doubt ; 
for no satisfactory theory of sense-experience can be gained 
while we ourselves are conscious that certain difficulties 
remain unfaccd, and one such difficulty lies ifi the possibility 
that sensing is never on any occasion an instance of knowing, 
even of the vaguest kind a possibility which is accentuated 
by certain facts about our sense-experience which we must 
now consider. 1 

The naive position itself clearly cannot be accepted. Neither 
can that modified form of it which holds that we sense directly 
and infallibly real features of real physical existents. The 
argument urged against the latter position was that if, for 
example, looking at a wall, we all see a real feature of it, namely 
its colour, then one and the same wall must be red, grey, and 
brown at one and the same time, since it is seen to possess 
these three distinct colours by three observers observing 
simultaneously. It is true, as was pointed out, that the difference 
in the seeing is due purely to a change in the circumstances in 
which the seeing occurs. But the fact that such circumstances 

1 In the discussion which follows I have been much influenced 
by the teaching of Professor H. A. Pri chard on the nature of the 
object in sensation (as yet unpublished). I readily and gratefully 
acknowledge the debt. I should add, however, that the consequences 
I draw from the theory (as also the actual formulation) are my own. 
And I cannot say how far Professor Pri chard would agree with me. 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 45 

can change what is seen was sufficient to prove our point at 
the time, namely, that seeing does not always provide us with 
reliable knowledge even of the colour of a thing, and that, 
therefore, our sensing of features, for example, our seeing of 
colours, is no infallible knowledge. By this means the theory 
that in seeing a colour I am invariably knowing a feature or 
quality of a real physical object was overthrown. 1 

But we must now consider the more important consequences 
that follow upon the difficulty illustrated here. Quite clearly, 
a red wall, if it be red, is neither grey nor brown, and yet we 
see it to be grey from a distance and brown again under a 
microscope. Therefore, we concluded, seeing a colour is no 
complete and infallible knowledge of a real feature of a real 
existent. Now, however, we need to ask a further question: Is 
it even partial knowledge? Common to all the critical theories 
discussed in the last two sections was the implication that sens- 
ing is knowing, but nevertheless an incomplete partial knowing 
that called out for completion by an intellectual effort of 
'adjusting' and judging. But can we rightly say that this instance 
of seeing a grey wall is 'partial' in this sense of providing us 
with what might of itself lead us to see the real colour of the 
wall? If we had never been near enough to see the wall as red, 
would the greyness we saw ever of itself suggest the redness ? 
Clearly not, for the error if 'error' it is of seeing the wall 
to be grey is no 'mistake' on my part that can be rectified by 
reflecting. However hard I reflect I shall not succeed in seeing 
the wall to be red from that distance. There is, as a matter of 
fact, no mistake about the experience; for I did see grey; and 

1 It might be argued by some thinkers that all three colours do 
exist someivhere in the real physical world, though not in one and 
the same space. The apparent contradiction would then be resolved, 
while the colours would still be physical. But even if this signified 
anything and we must confess that we find it difficult to attach 
any meaning to it yet the same problem remains. How are we to 
determine which of the three colours belongs to that space which 
the wall itself fills ? And the fact that the problem arises at all shows 
that we do not know in sensation directly and infallibly the real 
colour of the real wall. This is all we seek to show. 



46 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

yet it is equally clear that I was not then knowing, nor even 
'partially' knowing, if the colour of the object is indeed red, 
or any colour other than grey. 

As this is an important point, we may illustrate it further, 
taking on this occasion an instance of hearing for we must 
make certain that what we say applies not merely to seeing, but 
also to all other instances of sensory experience. Suppose X 
and Y both hear (speaking unphilosophically) one and the same 
noise. X says, "That is a pistol being fired. " Y might reply, 
"No, that was not a sharp enough report to have come from a 
pistol. You have inferred wrongly." X might then reflect and 
perhaps admit that Y was right. He would realize that he had 
mistaken a dull sound for the sharper-sounding report of the 
pistol. But now, we may suppose, X suddenly becomes par- 
tially deaf, unknown to himself. Again they both hear a noise ; 
for Y it is loud, for X it is not. If Y now tells Xthat the noise is 
loud, X will not believe him, and however much X reflects in 
this case, by no reflection whatever will he come to think that 
the sound was loud. That is to say, both X and Y are absolutely 
certain about what they heard; ex hypothesi they hear the 
sound produced by the same external something; and yet they 
do not hear the same sound. "But", it will be said, "X is deaf; 
the conditions under which he hears are abnormal and, if he 
was aware of this, he would give way to Y." That is certainly 
so. But the very fact that a change in the physiological con- 
ditions can thus produce a change in the sensation means that 
X, at least in this case, was not knowing one and the same 
external object with Y when he was hearing, for he was abso- 
lutely certain (and not only partially) that he was not hearing a 
loud noise, whereas if normal he would have heard a loud 
noise. X, therefore, we must conclude, is in this case simply 
not knowing; and by this we do not mean that he has fallen 
into error, or has inferred wrongly. Certainly, such false infer- 
ences may well occur later as a part of his whole experience of 
sensing, which, taken thus as a whole, is invariably wider than 
simply seeing a colour or hearing a sound. We only mean that 
in the bare hearing of the sound as such X is neither knowing 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 47 

nor, strictly speaking, erring. 1 In that particular his experience 
is not a cognitive one. What X hears is not what Y hears, yet 
neither is making a mistake. X as truly heard the slight sound 
as Y the loud. Therefore, if there is a real noise which they 
might be said to be 'knowing,' one of them (in this case, we 
suppose, X) is not knowing it when he hears a noise, not even 
'partially', or vaguely, or, again, half-erroneously. 

When, that is to say, I see in abnormal conditions, I am not, 
as barely seeing a colour, knowing any external real thing or 
any real feature of such an external. I do not even 'half-know' 
this feature, or know it vaguely. But clearly, when once this 
position is established, doubts must immediately arise about 
the character of sensing in normal circumstances. For can we 
admit the implication involved in the preceding paragraph, 
namely, that a difference in the external circumstances, physio- 
logical and physical, of itself produces this radical difference 
in the inward nature of sensing, making it in the one case 
knowledge and in the other an experience which is purely non- 
cognitive? Does it not seem absurd to suppose that sensing 
is knowing when I see the colour red under normal conditions 
to revert to the first example and that it is not knowing but 
something else when the other observers see the colours brown 
and grey? Again, if I look at a rose in light that is gradually 
fading, when I first look it has a fresh red tint, then I see it take 
on a darker shade, and ultimately it will become indiscernible 
from the blackness around it. Now in such a case it would 
surely be false to hold that when I saw the red rose I was 
knowing, while as soon as I began to see it 'changing its colour' 
I was no longer knowing, but experiencing a completely differ- 
ent experience. If it be correct to hold that in abnormal cases 
of sensing I am, purely in so far as I see a colour or hear a 
sound, not knowing a real physical object nor a real feature of 
it, it would seem necessary to add that in normal cases the 
experience and content being of the same general character as 

1 When I talk of 'knowing' here I mean, of course, knowing in 
the sense in which the experience claims to be knowing that is, 
knowing the externally real. 



48 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

in the abnormal case I also have no such knowledge. In a 
word, seeing a colour, hearing a sound, tasting a taste, smelling 
a smell, and feeling a resistance, are none of them cognitive 
experiences as such', they give us no knowledge of external 
physical objects. When, for example, I see a colour, just in so far 
I know no physical object, either as a whole or in part. 

"But", it may be objected, "what I know in sensing is nothing 
external; it is a sensum or sense-datum, something merely 
in the mind. Yet sensing is none the less definitely a knowing. 
I know the sensum." Such a view, of course, would be very 
different from what we mean ordinarily by calling sensation 
knowing. Ordinarily, we should mean that in sensation we 
know the real external world and no mere mental 'world'. But 
can we accept this much modified view ? Are we justified in 
calling sensation knowing even in this sense? We doubt it. 
Once again we must recall that the discussion io about the mere 
seeing of a colour, hearing of a sound, and so on. Now, no doubt 
there is knowing in the sensory experience taken as a whole. 
We shall shortly point out what elements of the experience 
are distinctly cognitive. But is just seeing a colour or hearing a 
sound knowing? Certainly, my consciousness that I now see 
is a knowing. Certainly, again, if 1 say "This is blue" I make a 
judgement, involving recognition, which at least claims to be 
true and is cognitive. But is seeing blue itself a knowing? 
We cannot admit that it itself, as such is. We do not know* 
'sensum' here, even if we see one. Seeing a colour, hearing a 
sound, belong rather to the realm of imagination than to that 
of knowing. And though the imaginative experience again 
taken as a whole involves cognitive elements, yet few would 
assert that imagining an image and knowing are synonymous. 

We might contrast knowing and sensing in greater detail. 
From the outset we have taken it for granted that a truth 'once 
true is always true*. Consequently, if we ever did have an experi- 
ence of knowing as such, then, we suppose, momentary changes 
of circumstance in the whole process by which knowing comes 
about would not affect the content known in any way. Truth, 
we suppose, is independent of the knower's particular location, 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 49 

and of whether it is known by this person or by that. Likewise, 
it does not depend upon the state of the knower's bodily organs 
nor upon the present condition of his immediate physical 
environment. But the content of sensation is completely lacking 
in the independence and absoluteness which thus characterise 
truth. What I see, for example, is dependent upon the particular 
set of conditions in which I happen to enjoy the sensory experi- 
ence, conditions having to do with my spatial position, the 
presence of light, the state of my eyes and optic nerves, and 
so on. Clearly enough, changes in the physico-physiological 
process accompanying each sensory experience have an effect 
upon the content 'given' me in sensation. But if seeing the 
colour, hearing the sound, were truly knowing, this would not 
be the case. For then the only changes of which we should 
be cognizant would be changes in the object known. The fact 
that changes iij the physico-physiological process produce 
changes in what we see, hear, and so on, is, in itself, sufficient 
proof that seeing colours, hearing sounds, are not instances of 
knowing. 

On these grounds, therefore, we feel obliged to conclude that 
the seeing of colours as such must not be conceived as a know- 
ing. 1 The same is true also of hearing a sound, smelling an 
odour, tasting a taste, and of any touch-sensation. As such 
these elements of sensory experiences are not cognitive. If I 
were merely seeing a colour I should not, in the first place, be 
directly knowing any actual feature of any real existent outside 
me (that is, of an independently real physical object), nor, in 
the second place, should I be providing myself thereby with 
content, which could be so worked upon and so developed by 
mind that in time I came to gain a knowledge of truth. This 
latter point is as evident as the former once we reflect upon the 
content of abnormal sensation. A colour-blind person, who 
sees (and always has seen) all things as grey, will never by 
reflecting upon the greyness, or by 'working' upon it in any 

1 Again, for the sake of safety, I had better repeat I do not mean 
that the whole sensory experience in an adult human mind of, for 
instance, seeing the red rose is completely non-cognitive. 



SO THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

way, make out the real colour of a real thing, if a real thing 
actually has a colour. His seeing of grey has, in itself, no cogni- 
tive value in determining the actual colour of the real thing 
if, again, it has a colour. But, clearly, what applies in the 
abnormal case applies equally well in the normal. For, to repeat 
a former question, how can we allow that identically the same 
experience is in the one case knowing (when circumstances 
external to it are normal) and in the other not knowing (when 
such external circumstances are abnormal)? And if it is not 
knowing not even knowing vaguely then colours, sounds, 
tastes, and so on, which make up the content of such sensing 
do not represent or illustrate the real in any way. Hence we 
see no need, and have no room, for a phenomenalist theory 
of knowledge. What sense 'gives', if we are thinking of colours, 
sounds, tastes, and so on, is nothing that either exactly or 
inexactly pictures the real, nor again can reflection upon a 
colour, or a sound, as such, lead to knowledge. We do not deny, 
however, as we shall proceed to make clear, that the sensory 
experience, taken as a whole, is definitely cognitive, and that 
we find in it the basis of much future knowledge. We hasten to 
mention this point in order to avoid misunderstanding. But, 
while we merely see colours, hear sounds, and so on, in so far 
we know nothing, either directly or indirectly. Consequently, 
we simply cannot say that we are dependent upon the seeing 
of colours, the hearing of sounds, and so on, for our knowledge 
of the external world, nor again that we are at first confined 
and limited in our knowledge to a world of sensory-appear- 
ances, or to the phenomenal, reflection upon which may lead 
us to full knowledge. 

It may, however, be objected that if we definitely adopt the 
position now being suggested, our difficulties will be infinitely 
more serious and acute; very soon all advance will become 
impossible. For we now affirm that experiencing the content 
of sensation (colours, sounds, smells, and so on) is not knowing 
the real, since such content is, so far as we know, neither the 
real itself nor an appearance pointing to the real and in some 
way illustrating it, whether distinctly or indistinctly. But, it will 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 51 

be asked, if we thus wholly deny that sensing is knowing do we 
not shut ourselves off from the possibility of ever knowing the 
external real ? What could we come to know of the world around 
us if we were incapable of sensing? It is a very old dictum that 
knowledge begins in sensation, and now we seem to be denying 
the assertion outright. Are we not really in a worse position 
than were those critics of the previous section who found them- 
selves shut up within a phenomenal world? And shall we not, 
in order to provide ourselves with some outlet, either have to 
accept their phenomenalism or wholly forget our doubts about 
sensation and return to the naive position ? 

By way of answer to this objection, and in order to make our 
position clear and definite, we may now set forth explicitly two 
further considerations relevant to the present issue. In the first 
place, we do not agree that sensation is the only outlet to reality. 
On the contrary^ if by 'outlet to reality* we mean knowledge 
of reality, and if by * sensation' we mean just the seeing of 
.colours, hearing of sounds, and so on, then we contend sensation 
is not even an 'outlet to reality', one amongst many. Seeing 
a colour, we have agreed, is not knowing; and, therefore, in 
this sense, it cannot be regarded as an outlet at all. But here an 
important reservation must be made. For, in the second place, 
it seems clear to us that the whole of any concrete sensory 
experience, as it occurs, is never the mere seeing of colours, 
the mere hearing of sounds, and so on. More is always involved 
in the experience. Consequently, to deny that seeing a colour 
is knowing, neither necessitates nor in any way justifies the 
further assertion, namely, that no particular sensory experience, 
as a concrete whole, can ever be a knowing. 

That the sensory experience as a whole is not merely a seeing 
of colours, or a hearing of sounds, and so on, can be proved 
conclusively by reconsidering a point already made. In merely 
seeing a colour there can be no mistake. I see the colour which 
I actually do see, and that is the end of the matter. Neverthe- 
less, it is a patent fact that any concrete sensory experience, 
taken as a whole, may, and very often does, contain error. But, 
if so, such a sensory experience must be more than the mere 



52 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

seeing of colours, hearing of sounds, and so on. For, once we 
admit that some of the experiences are erroneous, we imply 
that they might have been true that is, we implicitly affirm 
their cognitive character. But if seeing the colour were the 
whole rather than a part only of the experience, this would be 
impossible, since we have already granted that seeing a colour 
is an instance neither of knowing nor of erring. The sensory 
experience as a whole, therefore, is a complex of which seeing 
the colour is only a part. 

The source of the error in this complex is in some instances 
fairly obvious. When, for example, I see a coloured patch in 
the distance and say "That is Jones,'* the whole experience, 
though its duration be exceedingly short, is a very complicated 
one, involving at least recollection, comparison, and recognition. 
Into such a complex act error may easily enter. For instance, 
I may have recalled wrongly or inadequately. took the person 
in the distance to be Jones because he is just that height, but 
I ought also to have remembered that Jones is not so broad- 
shouldered. In other instances, however, the source of the 
error is not so obvious. Especially difficult to understand and 
explain, is that more fundamental type of error, whose exis- 
tence has already been noted by us. We believe, however, that 
much light can be thrown upon the character of the sensory 
experience in general by a thorough-going analysis of this 
latter error. We refer to the error involved when X and Y 
to revert to the former example hear what we should describe 
(when off our guard) as one and the same sound differently. 
There is no mistaking, yet both cannot be correct, if it really is 
the same sound. The truth is, of course, that all talk about one 
and the same sound in this context is false. X hears one sound 
and Y another. Their experiences differ in content and, in so 
far, neither errs. Nevertheless, we should naturally say, X is 
making a mistake. But on what grounds do we make this asser- 
tion? Why should we tend to think that X is in error? Clearly, 
because, in the first place, we assume throughout that X in 
hearing is knowing (or erring about) some externally-existent 
noise, and that Y in hearing is also knowing (or erring about) 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 53 

this same external existence; and because, in the second place, 
we take it for granted that in knowing the object is independent 
of the mind knowing. Consequently, it seems evident to us 
and to X and Y themselves that they ought both to hear exactly 
the same sound. If they do not, one of them is erring. In this 
case we judge that X is erring, because the noise is loud not 
only for Y but for many others as well. 

The error, that is to say, is connected with, being indeed the 
immediate consequence of, the conviction, natural to us, that 
when we see a colour or hear a sound we are knowing something 
existing really in total independence of our sensing. If X and Y 
believed that the sounds they heard were dependent on the 
sensory experience, if they supposed them identical in nature 
with the images of our imaginations and dreams, there could 
have been no cause for disagreement between them. For it is 
in no way necessary for two men to imagine the same noise 
at the same time. The disagreement came about only because 
both of them claimed, in hearing the noise, to be knowing 
something real, independent of them, something 'objective' 
as opposed to the 'subjective'. That is to say, the real cause 
of the disagreement lay in their common conviction a con- 
viction shared by all unreflecting persons that in hearing a 
sound we arc ipso facto knowing the physically real world 
which is independent of us as knowing it. In the sensory 
experience we feel convinced of the immediate presence of the 
external, and the alleged error of X is only to be understood 
in the light of this conviction. X is not really more mistaken 
than Y, but we should naturally consider him to be mistaken 
because both X and Y, we suppose, are hearing the same external 
something and so ought to hear the same noise and because 
most of us hear the same noise as Y. 1 That is to say, when actu- 
ally we are justified only in the belief that we hear a noise or see 
a colour, we invariably talk and act as if we were hearing some- 
thing real outside us and seeing a coloured something, a some- 

1 Even here a difficulty arises on reflection. For how can we possibly 
know that, for example, hearing a loud noise, or, again, seeing a red 
colour, is the same experience for all of us ? 



54 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

thing which exists independently of our seeing it. And we talk 
in this manner because we are convinced at the time that the 
external real is being known by us. It is the independence which 
we attribute to this 'something', which leads us to expect a 
conformity between our sensory experiences and to suspect 
ourselves of error when this conformity is missing, when, for 
example, on different occasions we see the same external 
something (as we think) to be grey and red, or hear the same 
something to be both loud and not loud. 

It is this conviction then which accounts for the fact that we 
so readily assume the world to consist of objects, which possess, 
as real qualities, colours, sounds, smells, tastes, resistances. 
We actually see colours, but we feel convinced at the same 
time that we are in contact with the real other than, and inde- 
pendent of, ourselves as sensing, and we consequently assume 
that we are seeing a world of independently real entities. The 
same is true of hearing, tasting, touching, and smelling. Here 
lies, surely, the deepest and most fundamental error of human 
experience, that when we see, for instance, a red patch we 
straightway believe we see a red physical object. In these pages 
the error is attributed to the fact that in this complex sensory 
experience we do not merely see the colour, but are also at one 
and the same time convinced of the existence of an externally 
real physical object and we immediately apply to it as a quality 
the content seen. 

Other explanations may be attempted. It may be said that 
colours look as if they were physical objects, and that sounds 
seem to be real things. But such an explanation of the source 
of the error seems absurd; a colour looks like nothing but a 
colour; a sound cannot seem to be anything other than a sound. 
This cannot be the true explanation. 

Another explanation that may be urged is that we become 
convinced of external things in so far as we realize the character 
of the space within which we see colours, since this space is so 
far independent of us as to make it impossible for us to arrange 
things spatially according to our private wishes. If we once 
realize this, it may be argued, it then becomes evident to us 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 55 

that we are dealing with an independent world, and it is natural 
for us to suppose that this independent world is filled with 
coloured objects. But this explanation is really no more adequate 
than the former. For even if we grant the first point that spatial 
arrangements are not created by us, but are known simultane- 
ously with the seeing, even so, our conviction that there exists 
before our eyes in sensation a world of independently real 
coloured objects cannot be the outcome of our realising that 
spatial arrangements are not our private creation. For when 
we imagine we are equally well compelled to set our imagery 
forth in space, yet there is in imagination no conviction that 
we have before us here and now an external independently 
real world of coloured objects. And we have no right whatever 
to assume that the space of the imagined world is a private 
creation of the mind, while that of the sensed world is indepen- 
dent of the mirld . 

One further explanation might be offered. We become con- 
vinced that an independently real world of coloured objects 
exists the moment we realize that the mind is not completely 
master of its sensory experiences. For instance, I cannot see 
what I want to see. I can imagine the deep purple of a kingly 
robe at the present moment, but I can only see the white which 
I (unphilosophically) take to be the colour of the paper before 
me and the brown of the table. However strong my desire to 
see purple, and however clear the image of purple before the 
'inward eye', I yet do not see purple. Once 1 realize this, it is 
urged, it then becomes natural for me to infer the existence 
of an independently real world outside consisting of so many 
coloured objects, and to conclude that I shall not see purple 
until something which is purple comes within my range of vision. 

Now it seems fairly obvious that what we see is in some 
measure independent of us. 1 Yet our belief in the existence of an 

1 Though, indeed, in certain abnormal cases the opposite seems 
to be the truth. For in hysteria the patient thinks he sees outside 
him what exists only in his imagination, and lunatics no doubt have 
often been convinced that they see the purple robes of sovereignty 
upon them although they are really dressed in ordinary clothes. But 
for the moment we can postpone consideration of these cases. 



56 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

independently real world in sensation can hardly have arisen 
from our realization of this fact. If the mind becomes aware of 
external existence only when it has explicitly realized that in 
sensation it is not free as to what it senses most of us would 
still be without the conviction that there exists an indepen- 
dently real world of coloured objects. Yet this conviction as a 
matter of fact seems always to be present, however far back 
we go in our experience, and certainly it exists long before 
we become aware of the mind's determination in sensation. 
Indeed, it seems rather ridiculous to suppose that at some early 
date in my mental history I chanced to be seeing yellow but 
wished to see, say, blue, and so concluded, since my wishes 
were frustrated, that this experience of seeing was, in part, 
out of my control, and that therefore there necessarily existed 
an independently real world of coloured objects. 

On the contrary, we seem to be convinced of'thc existence of 
an independently real world consisting of so many separate 
coloured objects simultaneously with our seeing the colour, 
and not by any inference from it. Therefore, w r hile this argu- 
ment from our determination ab extra in sensation may be of 
great value as confirming our conviction that there exists an 
independently real world, we cannot admit that the conviction 
originated with it. It is obviously prior to it. From the first 
we seem to feel certain that there is a world around and outside 
of us as sensing, and we implicitly believe that the colours we 
see belong as qualities to the world about whose existence 
we are so convinced. In a word, we straightway see, so we 
suppose, a coloured world out there. 

These attempted explanations, therefore, have all proved 
unsatisfactory. None the less the facts which they seek to 
explain remain indisputable. The sensory experience is not 
merely a seeing of colours, a hearing of sounds, and so on. 
There is always present in each and every sensory experience 
that which claims, at least, to be knowledge. Throughout we 
are convinced that we are here and now apprehending a world 
of objects. The latter are not created by us, and are not of the 
character as the images of our imagination, but are 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 57 

independent of us and, in this sense, outside us waiting to 
be apprehended. Furthermore, we are also convinced that these 
objects possess various sensory qualities, colours, sounds, tastes, 
and so on which we apprehend in sensation. 

Now how far are these convictions valid ? Are they justified 
and warranted by the rest of our experiences, and by our 
later reflections upon the sensory experience? It was pointed 
out earlier that we are frequently convinced without actually 
knowing at the time. Error would not be error were we not 
convinced whilst erring that we were knowing the truth. 1 But 
do we know the truth or are we in error when we are convinced 
in the sensory experience that we now apprehend an inde- 
pendently real world of coloured objects? 

To this one question there are two parts. Firstly, do I see a 
world of independently real coloured objects ? Or to consider 
another of the Senses do I taste an independently real object 
which has, as one of its qualities, a certain taste? At the un- 
reflective stage we are convinced that such is the case. The 
colour, the sound, the taste, the odour, the resistance belong 
to the independently real object as so many qualities. The 
apple before me is itself red, sweet, hard, and so on, quite apart 
from my seeing, my tasting, and my touching. But is our con- 
viction sufficient evidence that the independent real does possess 
these properties? We have already answered this question. In 
the argument of the present section we have tried to make it 
clear that such a conviction is wholly unwarranted by the facts 
of our sensory experience. The fact that I see colours does not 
justify me, surely, in holding that the independently real world 
is a world of coloured objects. I only believe that it does when 
I take it for granted that the seeing is itself knowing, whereas 
reflection shows that it is nothing of the kind. It may scil! be 
admitted, however, that the object possesses some property or 
quality which causes me to see a certain colour at the present 
moment and in the present circumstances. (Were it not so I 

1 Consequently, doubt is not error, nor is suspension of judgement, 
for in such experiences there is no conviction that we now know. For 
the moment I leave out of consideration error in probable judgements. 



58 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

could not begin to explain why it is that I see one object to be 
red and another to be blue in like circumstances. It may even 
prove true that actually independently real objects are coloured, 
though at present I certainly do not know this.) Our only point 
now is that in merely seeing a colour we do not know any real 
quality of an independently real existence directly, and that it is 
pure assumption on our part to suppose that we do. We are 
not, therefore, justified in our first conviction that the indepen- 
dently real consists of so many coloured objects. We have not, 
of course, proved this conviction of a coloured world to be 
definitely erroneous, but we have shown that it is pure assump- 
tion and so quite possibly erroneous. That we immediately 
see an independently real world of coloured objects must be 
written dow r n as a completely unverified assumption. 

But, secondly, a more important question remains to be 
considered in this connection. Do we really apprehend an 
external existence whilst sensing? We certainly feel convinced 
that we do in an unreflective mood. If I close my eyes and 
begin to imagine I know that all the occurrences imagined 
by me belong to a world of imagination within my mind. But 
once I open them I am convinced that I look out upon a world 
other than, and independent of, my mind. Now even though 
it be admitted that we do not see and hear actual qualities of 
the real objects outside, can we not assert without fear of con- 
tradiction, that in the sensory experience we apprehend the 
existence of such objects and of an external independently 
real world ? 

Our conviction that such is the case seems so natural, so 
universal, and so certain, as to appear unassailable. Nevertheless, 
certain considerations which we must now make cannot but 
throw doubt even upon this conviction. In certain cases of 
hysteria the patient is convinced that he sees what can only 
be the creation of his imagination. He sees occurring externally 
to him and, as he believes, independently of him, happenings 
which we know could not occur anywhere except in his dis- 
ordered imagination. Here then is a case of imagining in which 
the person imagining is convinced that he is now knowing 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 59 

occurrences in an independently real world. Or we may take 
the more normal experience of dreaming. I may dream of many 
strange events and 'see' them all occur before my eyes in the 
world outside and around me, but when I wake up I realize that 
I have been dreaming and have actually seen nothing outside me 
in independence of my own imagination. But if this is so, then 
clearly in dreaming and in hysteria my conviction actually 
misleads me. And if it be proved at fault in hysteria and dream- 
ing, my faith in my conviction whilst sensing must also be shaken. 
May not the whole of my experience be a dream which I myself 
spin out of my imagination ? May not my conviction of an out- 
side world be as illusory in the sensory experience as it is in 
dreaming or in hysteria? 

Now as long as these questions remain unanswered we 
have no right to claim for our conviction absolute validity. 
We can no longer be theoretically and absolutely certain that 
the sensory experience is in part an apprehension of an inde- 
pendently real world around us. But again and this now 
becomes a matter of vital importance for our argument we 
have still less right to deny this assertion outright. Because our 
conviction is illusory in dreaming and in hysteria we have no 
right to assume that it is equally illusory when sensing ; because 
our experience is defective in one respect we cannot argue that 
it must be defective in all respects. And certainly we have no 
right to infer that the world about whose independent existence 
we are so convinced in the sensory experience is actually 
dependent upon me and is identical in character with the world 
of imagination. With full confidence, then, we can neither 
assert nor deny the existence of an independently real world 
if all the information we possess is that given us in the sensory 
experience. 

Nevertheless, though we are conscious of the fact that com- 
plete knowledge in this connection is out of the question at 
present, we can yet claim that one position is more likely to be 
true than another. Indeed, it is now becoming obvious that 
most of what we ordinarily call knowing is not knowing in 
the strict sense that is, knowing apodeictically but is rather 



60 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

the determining of what is most probably true in any set of 
circumstances. It would be absurd, therefore, to deny the 
possibility and the actual existence of what w^e term 'opinion' 
retaining the term 'knowledge* for absolute and certain 
knowledge. Now our first conviction that there exists an 
independently real world the conviction that makes solipsism 
appear from the first an absurd theory becomes, upon reflec- 
tion, an opinion whose truth is extremely probable. Doubt 
creeps in when we recall such experiences as dreaming and 
hysteria. Yet, \vhile we cannot be certain, it seems exceedingly 
probable that an independently real w r orld exists, and exceed- 
ingly improbable that the whole of our life should be nothing 
but a dream. All the rest of my experience seems to confirm 
my belief that there are other existences, independent of me. 
Certainly, metaphysical speculation may lead me to say that 
the Real in, or the Essence (and so the explanation) of, all that 
lies about me as well as of my own existence is Mind. Even so, 
it would remain extremely probable (though not certain) that 
/ am not the mind that brought into being these things around 
me, as I bring into being an occurrence in a dream. And though 
I have not complete and absolute certainty on this point I live 
out my life on this hypothesis, and thus far apart from the 
doubt already mentioned no other has arisen. Here, therefore, 
is something which seems exceedingly probable. But it is not 
absolutely certain knowledge. It also must be written down 
in the last resort as something taken to be true, without our 
being completely certain of its truth. 1 

Is there, then, anything of which we are completely certain 
in sensation? Obviously, the moment we reflect, we are com- 
pletely certain of one fact, namely, that we do have this experi- 
ence. For whether awake or dreaming, in a normal or an abnor- 

1 There are, we repeat, degrees of probability. And we may safely 
say that this latter assumption is more likely to be true than our 
earlier assumptions, namely, that independently real objects actually 
possess as qualities the colours we think we see them to possess. On 
reflection, and as our knowledge increases, this latter assumption 
seems to become less and less probable. 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 61 

mal state, I do now see this particular colour, and I know that 
I see the colour. But this knowledge hardly occurs in the most 
primitive forms of the sensory experience. It comes later. It 
presupposes a reflective mood, and a capability of distinguish- 
ing between what is external to me as experiencing and what 
is internal. But this explicit distinction is not made at the lowest 
levels. It is certainly assumed in thinking of the physical object. 
Yet it is only later, surely, that it becomes explicit. The truth 
seems to be that the question of the dependence or indepen- 
dence of these physical objects and real entities which I think 
I see upon my mind does not really arise in these primitive 
experiences. It only arises explicitly for the reflective philo- 
sophical person. And in just the same way we have at this 
level no explicit idea of self, and cannot be said then to feel 
certain that we now enjoy a particular experience for example, 
seeing a colons. Thus it would be hardly correct to say that 
throughout the sensory experience we find a knowledge of the 
self as enjoying a sensation. But is there, then, any certain 
knowledge in these lowest sensory experiences ? 

We believe an affirmative answer must be given to this ques- 
tion. We doubt the existence of coloured objects. Furthermore, 
the moment the matter becomes explicit we find it possible to 
doubt that in the sensory experience we have a knowledge of 
independently real physical objects. But present in all sensory 
experience we find one conviction that we have never yet 
succeeded in doubting. It is the conviction of real being. In 
the sensory experience we are aware of existence (whether 
internal or external to mind). We believe we know much more, 
we 'see', so we suppose, coloured things. This, however, can 
be doubted. But that sense-experience involves an awareness 
of existence cannot be doubted. It is so far cognitive. That is 
to say, if we take the sensory experience of the most unreflec- 
tive person and abstract from it all that he thinks he knows, 
but that we see reason to doubt, there will still remain a core 
of certain knowledge which cannot be doubted. Viewed cogni- 
tively, sensory experience is largely erroneous, but it is not 
completely so. 



62 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

"But", it will be objected, "what does this person know? 
One cannot know a that unless one knows its what. One cannot 
know bare existence, one can only know something having 
definite qualities. But the only certain knowledge you allow 
the mind in sensation is that of bare existence. Yet no mind 
can ever know bare existence as such. For as such bare existence 
is just nothing." We admit the strength of the criticism and 
do not wish to avoid it. Our answer is that the sensory experi- 
ence is never merely the knowledge of bare existence. Bare 
existence is not the content of the experience. It is the result 
of our abstraction and analysis. What we believe we know 
when we sense is a world of sensible objects. But we have 
shown that we are not justified in our belief. All we can definitely 
and justifiably be certain of is that actually something exists. 
The mind, however, unjustifiably but very naturally, 'sees' 
in the content 'given' by the senses the 'stuff 'of the real, and, 
as a consequence, believes itself to possess a more extended 
knowledge of the real world in sense-experience than it does 
actually possess. 

If it now be added that every other human experience 
involves so much knowledge, since there is no experience in 
which we are not aware of existence and are not apprehending 
some reality of some sort, we shall not deny this. What we 
claim for the barest sensory experience that can be imagined, 
from the point of view of true and certain knowledge, is very 
little indeed. But we believe that it was necessary in a full 
and complete analysis of the sensory experience to mention 
this essential component of each sensory experience, however 
bare. 

We are now in a position to carry out a three-fold analysis 
of the sensory experience taken as a whole. In the first place, 
we note a certain determination or affection of the mind in 
sensation. We find ourselves compelled to see blue on one 
occasion and yellow on another. However strongly we will we 
cannot will to see a particular colour. The mind in sensing is 
not completely master of the situation ; in some measure it is 
determined. Here is one essential feature of the sensory expe- 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 63 

rience which it is always dangerous to disregard. A second 
feature is the seeing of the colour, the hearing of the sound, 
and so on. We are not merely determined, but we also see. This 
seeing of a colour could never occur were we not beings who 
possessed the qualities and capabilities (both mental and 
physiological) necessary for its occurrence. So also with hearing 
a sound, tasting a taste, and so on. 1 To be determined is not 
enough. But when we, who possess these qualities, are deter- 
mined in this manner, then we see, hear, taste, and so on. In 
the third place, there is a cognitive side to the sensory experi- 
ence as a whole. This is not the seeing of a colour, but is to 
be distinguished from it; for seeing a colour is not knowing, 
neither is hearing the sound as such. The sensory experience 
as a whole, however, is never the mere seeing of a colour. 
Throughout we are at least making claims to know. We have 
been led to conclude that most of these claims are invalid. 
Much of the so-called 'knowledge' in the sensory experience 
is really probable only and ought better to be termed 'opinion'. 
Its defect is that it does not carry with it complete certainty. 
Moreover, some portion of what we naively claim to be know- 
ledge is definitely error. Indeed, only one claim seems to be 
unquestionably valid for all cases of sensory experience, namely, 
that in it w r e know real being. (For the sake of completeness, 
however, we should also add that already we, at least, opine, 
if not know, 2 temporal and spatial relations, identities, causal 
relations, and the like in the sensory experience.) Thus the 
sensory experience taken as a whole possesses definitely a 
cognitive feature ; and this is especially true if within 'cognition' 
we include, as is usual, opinion, and even error. 

Also, it is necessary to mention the activities of mind qua 

1 I have not sought to give any account of the nature of these 
necessary qualities. Such an account would definitely go beyond the 
scope of this work. All I wish to show is that this feature of the whole 
sensory experience is distinguishable (though not separable) from the 
knowing present. 

J At present we need not discuss whether this is knowledge or 
opinion. 



64 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

comparing, relating, and recollecting within the whole sensory 
experience. These clearly pertain to its cognitive side. We have 
been considering the sensory experience in its barest forms, 
yet in no case, it would seem, are the above activities wholly 
absent. In the more developed forms of the sensory experience, 
as, for instance, in adult experience, they are obviously present. 
We gain knowledge and come to an opinion mediately after 
much comparison, recollection, and reflection. We shall con- 
sider the mediation involved in greater detail in the next 
chapter. But it also seems to be present even in our earliest 
sensory experiences, especially so if these call forth any 
explicit and significant statement on our part, however 
simple; for instance, ''How hot!" "This is blue." A 
discussion of this matter, however, would be irrelevant at the 
present moment. 

We thus acknowledge the existence of these* activities in the 
sensory experience, but postpone consideration of them to 
the next chapter. It is as well, how r ever, to point out at once 
that we do not intend to adopt the further position, sometimes 
held, that the purpose of these activities is to help us create out 
of the content 'given' by the senses a significant sensible object. 
We have throughout combated this view. There is no more 
serious error in the realm of epistemology, we should like to 
suggest, than to suppose that knowledge comes about by 
'working* upon the sensory qualities provided by our senses. 
The ultimate consequence of such a view, as we have pointed 
out, is always the same; we find ourselves shut off from the real 
world and confined to the phenomenal. And this consequence, 
we think, results from the failure to analyse the sensory experi- 
ence properly. It is due to mistaking what is not cognitive in 
the experience for a cognitive feature of it. The colours seen, 
the sounds heard, and so on, may be termed, if we wish it, 
'appearances'. But they are not to be thought of, on any account, 
as in themselves leading us to, or in any way suggesting, 
knowledge of the real, they provide such knowledge neither in 
part nor wholly, neither, again, directly nor indirectly by way 
of copy and illustration. Nor, lastly, can we gain any knowledge 



THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE 65 

whatever of the real by reflecting on such colours and sounds 
in themselves, however hard we reflect. Whatever knowledge 
itself is, it is not the seeing of a colour, nor is it any kind of 
intellectual 'working' upon the bare colours, sounds, and so 
on, provided in sensation. We should rid ourselves of the 
misleading idea that we know a half-real shadow-world in the 
sensory experience, and that by 'working* upon this shadow- 
world we may in time come to know the real which lies behind 
it. As much as we know in the sensory experience is the real 
itself and no half-real. And if anything helps us in future, then 
it can only be the knowledge we actually do gain. 

At present, then, as the result of our reflections in this chapter, 
we have little to say about the nature of knowing. For that 
which is knowing in the sensory experience is so minute and 
so inextricably woven into the texture of the whole experience 
that it is exceedingly difficult to detach it in order to observe 
it as it is in its own nature. Hence, though we may feel 
convinced that every sensory experience involves a knowing, 
namely (at least), the apprehension of the existence of a real 
world, yet we cannot hope to gain much positive information 
about the nature of knowing from scrutinizing it as it is em- 
bedded in the sensory experience. It would indeed be foolish 
to expect the nature of knowledge to be best revealed in that 
experience wherein it seems least present. In the sensory 
experience knowledge is at a minimum. Consequently, if we 
wish to discover the nature of knowing it would be wise to turn 
away from the sensory experience. There are other human 
experiences where the knowing involved can be more easily 
studied. In the sensory experience the cognitive element does 
not even predominate; for, undoubtedly, the characteristic 
feature of any sensory experience is the sensing of colours, 
sounds, tastes, and so on. Thus the knowing in it is hidden 
and encumbered by what is not knowing. We need to find an 
experience, in which knowing will be freed from some at least 
of the encumbrances that surround it in the sensory, so that it 
can be more easily examined and observed. 

For these reasons we must content ourselves at the end of 



66 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

this chapter with the negative information which is all that we 
have thus far obtained. The sensory experience, we conclude, 
certainly does not present us with that example of complete 
and perfect knowledge for which we seek. At most, it can only 
provide us with one brief glimpse of our quarry in the distance. 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 

THE argument of the preceding chapter has thrown little 
light upon the character of knowing. On the whole, it would 
seem untrue to say that the sensory experience is ever com- 
pletely non-cognitive. But what is not knowing in the experience 
is so closely bound up with the actual knowing present, and 
is so frequently confused with it, that the use of the sensory 
experience as an instance of knowing is unsatisfactory and even 
dangerous. For it is only with difficulty that we free ourselves 
from the naive and completely misleading tendency, so deeply 
rooted in our minds, to regard the bare seeing of a colour as 
itself an infallible knowledge of the external world. The first 
truth that must be learnt is this negative one that knowing is 
something wholly different in character from merely seeing a 
colour, hearing a sound, and so on. And since such bare 
sensing is the most prominent and the most characteristic 
feature of the sensory experience (though never the whole 
of it) the latter cannot but prove a very poor instance of 
knowing. 

Now a far more valuable instance, it may be said, is to be 
found in discursive reasoning. Here, certainly, is a conscious 
attempt at knowledge. Prima facie, it seems to consist in the 
effort to attain further knowledge indirectly (that is, through 
another or other known truths) when the direct approach is 
impossible. Discursive reasoning is in this respect synonymous 
with mediation, and most of the knowledge (and opinion) 
gained by mankind seems to be gained in this way. For 
instance, in our developed sensory experiences the presence 
of discursive reasoning is obvious. We succeed in making new 
assertions through comparing and relating the present * given* 
with our other experiences; we discover unity in differences 
and differences in unity; we 'see* things in a wider context 
and relation; and thus argue from truths already known to 
others not yet known. The sensory experience in its concrete- 
ness, as it occurs in the ordinarily developed adult mind, is as 
much discursive reasoning as it is sensing. And as our know- 

67 



68 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

ledge increases so we find greater need for discursive reasoning. 
Now, if such be the case, a careful examination of discursive 
reasoning or mediation should give us real insight into the 
nature of knowledge. It must be the instance of knowing for 
which we seek. 

In the present chapter we propose to examine this claim. 
What is discursive reasoning? Is it through and through 
knowing and nothing but knowing ? Or is it a complex process 
like sense-experience, of which knowing is part only? If the 
former, how best can we describe the knowing? If the latter, 
then, again, what characteristics belong to the knowing 
involved, and, in addition, what other feature or features 
different from knowing are present and what function do they 
fulfil ? These are the problems that must engage our attention 
in the present chapter. 

Before we can proceed, however, to thek- detailed con- 
sideration, and before we endeavour to give a more definite 
meaning to the terms used thus far in describing discursive, 
reasoning, certain very important preliminaries must be dis- 
cussed. These are themselves of the greatest interest from our 
point of view, because of the further light they throw on the 
nature of knowledge. 

For, firstly, how do we come by that prior knowledge pre- 
supposed once we conceive discursive reasoning to be the 
gaining of new knowledge through truth already known ? The 
prior knowledge, it may be answered, was itself known in 
some earlier mediate process based upon still earlier know- 
ledge. But clearly this cannot go on for ever. There must be 
a basis, which is known not by mediation but by some other 
means, upon which all our mediate knowledge rests as on a 
foundation. But how did this first knowledge come about? 
And is it wholly different from the knowledge found within 
the process of discursive reasoning? If it be so, is it a better 
instance of knowing than discursive reasoning? And are there 
then many kinds of knowing, each distinct from the others ? 

In the second place, what exactly is the content of the 
knowledge presupposed in mediation ? It is evident from what 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 69 

has been said that some knowledge must always be presupposed 
in mediation. But knowledge of what? The difficulty in seeking 
to answer this question arises from the fact that the prior 
knowledge is required for at least two purposes, the one 
radically different from the other. In the first place, we require 
a logically secure foundation for the structure we are about 
to build by discursive reasoning. Unless the basis and principle 
of procedure are logically valid, the whole structure will be 
unsound. We must know beforehand what is and what is 
not logically valid. It is this kind of prior knowledge which 
we shall discuss in the first section. But, in addition, the 
discursive reasoning cannot proceed unless some * stuff* is 
known beforehand. The thought-process begins with some- 
thing already known, not only with a knowledge of the 
logically valid, but also with a certain definite content. This 
content, it is usual to suppose, has already been gained by the 
mind in 'experience'. Before the process of mediation could 
ever begin the mind has already 'gained certain data'. Now 
such language is distressingly vague. What is this 'experience'? 
And how does it provide the 'stuff' beforehand? The more 
nominalist type of answer to these questions will engage our 
attention throughout the second section, but no final answer 
can be given until the nature of mediation or discursive 
reasoning itself has been made clear in the third section of 
this chapter. 

I 

The Prior Knowledge of Principles 

In this section we shall consider the knowledge of the 
basic principles presupposed in all discursive reasoning. We 
shall show, firstly, why such prior knowledge is necessary. 
In the second place, we shall defend the thesis that such 
principles are necessarily universal and all-pervasive features 
of real being. Thirdly, we shall discuss the nature of the act 
of knowing by which the principles are apprehended. 



70 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

We may best begin by reiterating a point already made, 
that any mediate process which is to provide us with demon- 
strable knowledge must rest ultimately on a sure foundation. 
And this means, in part at least, that as we advance step by 
step in the argument we are throughout guided by sound 
principles. Long before we bother to formulate these principles 
precisely, however, we apprehend the truths they embody, 
for example, that a thing cannot contradict itself, and we 
make use of them when reasoning discursively. Indeed, it is 
only when we are compelled to defend our position or when 
the sceptic in us awakes that we realize how all along we have 
proceeded on the understanding that certain primary principles 
which we now seek to formulate in precise terms were true, 
and how, throughout, the validity of our reasoning depends 
upon their truth. But it is clear that the ultimate source of 
our assurance as to the validity of any reasoning process lies 
always in some principle (or principles) which we see to be 
indubitably true. 1 Consequently, if we affirm that mediation 
yields demonstratively valid knowledge, then we presuppose 
the existence of a prior knowledge, namely, that of the first 
principles of reasoning, upon which our discursive reasoning 
depends and by which it is guided throughout. The necessity 
of this prior knowledge is obvious. 

Moreover, this prior knowledge of the principles must be 

1 We do not mean that these principles are primary premisses in 
the sense of starting-points for any particular science. They are 
rarely, if ever, premisses at all. Every particular science has its own 
primary premisses. For instance, if we take the particular ground for 
any statement in arithmetic, this will be grounded on another state- 
ment, and ultimately we shall come to one about perhaps the nature 
of the unit used, or again about arithmetical progression and scale. 
These final statements may be regarded as primary premisses of the 
science. But they, and their like in other sciences, are not what we 
have now in mind. The principles according to which we reason in 
any mediate process are not confined to any particular science. Nor 
are they first premisses or definite starting-points. They are rather 
principles in accordance with which and not from which we invariably 
argue. 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 71 

completely certain and beyond all doubt. For if any demon- 
stratively valid knowledge is ever to be possible it must be 
based on our conviction that the foundations of our reasoning 
are secure; and if we are not certain of these foundations, if 
we have the slightest cause for doubt, then we can put no 
confidence in the structure erected on them, however securely 
built it appear; we cannot, that is to say, but be sceptical. 
Furthermore, in the present case, we cannot save ourselves by 
making a show of suspending our judgement. It may be true 
that these principles are not valid; but if we once suspect 
this, then, while we continue to suspect, we must also doubt 
all knowledge gained discursively. We must, therefore, if we 
wish to affirm that discursive reasoning does give knowledge, 
also affirm that the first principles necessarily presupposed 
within it are valid. Thus, to all intents and purposes, the 
implicit denial present in the hesitation of one who withholds 
his judgement is in this case of like nature with and produces 
.the same result as the explicit denial of the sceptic. 1 

But, granting the necessity of a prior indubitable know- 
ledge of such principles, what do we know when we know 
them? In the first place, since we are dealing with an instance 
of knowledge, the object in this case must be identical with 
the object of all other knowledge, namely, reality. In the 
second place, this view is confirmed by a further reflection. 
Unless the principles are valid, as holding of the real world, 
then no knowledge of that real world can be gained discur- 
sively. We have taken it for granted that knowledge must be 
of what is. Consequently, the mediation could not provide us 
with knowledge if the principles in accordance with which it 
proceeds did not hold of the real. If we started with principles 
not holding of the real and allowed ourselves to be guided by 

1 We may here add, as something that follows obviously upon the 
above reflection, that the first principles cannot be 'ordering con- 
ceptions' in the sense of hypotheses made by us that may or may not 
be true. The first principles must be true, or else all the rest of our 
thinking is invalid. We do not seek to establish them by mediate 
reasoning, as is the case with hypotheses, but we establish all that is 
established mediately by reasoning according to them. 



72 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

them, then discursive reasoning would become, at best, a form 
of intellectual entertainment, pleasant enough in itself perhaps, 
but possessing, from the point of view of knowledge gained, 
no value whatsoever. It could tell us nothing about reality. 

It follows, therefore, that in knowing the principles accord- 
ing to which we reason we must be knowing certain charac- 
teristic features of the real world as it is. We cannot avoid 
this conclusion without denying the very possibility of know- 
ledge through discursive reasoning. We certainly could not 
avoid it by asserting that the principles hold of a half-real 
phenomenal or 'sensory' world immediately before us in 
thinking. For we have earlier 1 agreed to reject all pheno- 
menalistic accounts of knowing. Knowledge, we contend, if it 
exists at all, is of the real, and not of what we know to be 
merely phenomenal. Hence, unless these principles, knowledge of 
which is presupposed as providing the foundation for mediation, 
are of the real, we cannot hope to gain knowledge discursively. 

In order to illustrate the matter further, we may consider 
the principles individually. The principle of Non- Contradiction 
is formulated thus: <( The same attribute cannot at the same 
time belong and not belong to the same subject and in the 
same respect." As thus formulated this is one of its earliest 
formulations (and surely its best) it is evident that the 
principle has to do with the real, and not with any merely 
ideal world. It does not apply merely to thought processes; 
though it does apply to them, since it applies to all things real. 
But the point is that in apprehending it we are apprehending 
a characteristic mark of what is. Reality, that is to say, is of 
such a nature that we are compelled never to admit patent 

1 In the second section of the first chapter. If the 'objective* world 
is conceived as a world of phenomena largely dependent upon the 
knower, no self-contradiction need then be involved in a theory 
which asserts that the principles holding in the 'objective' world are 
themselves the consequence of mind's synthetic activity. But we 
reject phenomenalism, and certainly should be contradicting ourselves 
if we put forward any such theory. The only possible position for us 
is the one set forth above. The principles known must be universal 
features of the real which we discover, 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 73 

contradictions into our thinking about it. The same is true of 
the principle of Identity "whatever is, is", or "a thing is 
what it is". The reference here is to real being, to everything 
that is. Anything possessing reality is what it is, and we cannot 
think it otherwise. Thirdly, we have the principle of Excluded 
Middle: "a subject either has or has not a certain attribute"; 
there is no third possibility. Here, again, knowledge of the 
principle is an apprehension of a fact about the real. 

Such are the three principles recognized by logicians as 
being the bases of all thought the so-called Laws of Thought, 1 
The use of this latter term must not be taken to imply that 
the laws are merely of thought, or ideal only as opposed to 
real. For, once again, what is meant when we emphasize the 
need for such Laws of Thought as a basis is that human 
thinking and reasoning could never provide knowledge of the 
real unless th$ mind already possessed in reasoning a clear 
apprehension of certain facts about the real. We never carry 
forward our processes of mediation in complete ignorance of 
the matter under consideration. Throughout we have know- 
ledge of the real, but in discursive reasoning we pass on to a 
fuller knowledge of it. And we may legitimately press this 
point further. Such prior knowledge gives us information as 
to the character which reality everywhere and always, uni- 
versally, possesses. Before we can begin to reason discursively 
w'e must (speaking logically) first know the real, and also know 
something which holds universally of it. The real must be 
knowable and known by the human mind, even with regard 
to certain universal features of it. This is the ultimate pre- 
supposition of all discursive reasoning. 

Such a conclusion seems inevitable. But what exactly does 
it signify? All knowledge gained demonstratively necessarily 

1 We emphasize the fact that they are the bases of all thought 
because their universality and all-pervasiveness is their distinguishing 
mark. And this must mean, we contend, that they hold of all reality. 
Whatever is real, whether it be 'subjective' or 'objective', must 
possess these features, and the mind cannot think of any real exist- 
ence without conceiving of it as identical and self-consistent. 



74 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

presupposes a knowledge of certain universal characteristics of 
reality, and if the former occurs, then clearly the latter already 
exists. Yet these obvious truths, we must now point out, 
throw no light on our actual knowing of the first principles. 
They simply show the necessity of that knowledge if further 
knowledge is to occur. Now, in the first place, it is still possible 
to doubt the occurrence of any further knowledge ; and in such 
a case the necessity for a prior indubitable knowledge of 
principles would not arise. This, however, is a position we 
have agreed to reject. But, in the second place, even if we 
admit the existence of an ever-growing body of certain know- 
ledge based ultimately on the principles, w r e can only argue 
from this to the necessary existence of the prior knowledge. 
We are given no information about the nature of that prior 
knowledge. The above argument can at most only confirm its 
existence by showing its necessity if knowledge has been 
gained demonstratively. Hence, to say that knowledge of the 
first principles is necessarily presupposed by all further know- 
ledge is not to describe its nature. And this point should be 
emphasized, since it is sometimes carelessly assumed that we 
have said all there is to say about knowledge of the principles 
when we say that it is necessarily presupposed in all demon- 
stration and therefore must exist. 

How, then, are we to describe this knowing? We have 
already learnt that it cannot be mediate knowledge. Obviously, 
we do not know the principles with the help of principles 
that is, through any process of demonstrative reasoning. Nor, 
again, can we say that the 'objective' world is itself mind- 
ordered, and that, therefore, the principles according to which 
the mind thinks are the very principles that order the 'object- 
ive' world. Finally, such knowledge cannot be 'given' by the 
senses; for they, if they 'give' any knowledge at all and we 
deny this 1 could only 'give' knowledge of the present, the 
'here-now', whereas in knowing the principles we know 

1 At the same time we, of course, admit that the determination of 
the mind in sensation is an occasion for knowing, and that the sensory 
experience, taken as a whole, is cognitive, 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 75 

universal and all-pervasive characteristics holding throughout 
reality. What, then, are we to say? How do we know, for 
instance, that one and the same attribute cannot both belong 
and not belong at one and the same time to the same subject 
in the same respect? We can only answer that we know it as 
something self-evident. We directly 'perceive' the truth of the 
statement, and know beyond the possibility of doubt that 
reality never contradicts itself. It is immediate apprehension 
of the truth. The mind apprehends directly by that knowing 
power which belongs to it this universal feature of the real. 

From the time we first begin to reason discursively, then, 
we know that the real world does not contradict itself, and we 
reason on this basis. Moreover, the fact that we do not at the 
time formulate this truth in precise logical terminology in no 
way deprives the knowledge we possess of its certainty. Our 
knowledge herE is no opinion to which we hold even though 
we realize its possible falsity; nor, again, is it Vague' or 
'indefinite'. It is definite enough, as our use of it in reasoning 
proves. It is certain knowledge that w r e may or may not possess. 
We either know or do not know it, but we cannot be said to 
know it dimly, for if we once see that what is real cannot 
contradict itself, then we cannot later gain any greater clearness 
or any greater certainty on this point. 1 

' Though we believe that this knowledge comes early in the mental 
history of a rational being, we do not wish to imply that it is innate. 
And, certainly, we should reject the view that because it is a self- 
evident truth that the real cannot contradict itself it must there- 
fore be innate. A truth's self-evidence in no way makes it innate. 
For, obviously, what is perfectly sclf-c\ident to a trained mind may 
be incomprehensible to the untrained. In the last section of this 
chapter we shall point out how much mental preparation is frequently 
necessary before the mind is enabled to apprehend the self-evident. 
And, no doubt, we should not have learnt that the real is non- 
contradictory had we not first experienced certain experiences (for 
instance, the sensory experience), so that we can hardly be said to 
know even this truth innately. It is a later discovery. Our poinr, 
however, is that from the first discovery of it our knowledge here is 
certain and indubitable a direct apprehension of one characteristic 
feature or mark of the real world. 



76 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

If, then, we ever have certain knowledge, we have it when 
in discursive reasoning we proceed on the understanding that 
the real does not contradict itself. But what proofs have we 
to offer whereby this claim may be substantiated? Obviously 
none, except simply the proof of our own compelling con- 
viction when we consider the matter. And if it be objected 
that the convictions of a fallible creature are an insufficient 
criterion, we can only reply that we cannot bring ourselves to 
admit the possibility of these principles being untrue. To deny 
them is to talk patent nonsense. To deny them significantly 
and not merely in words would be to conceive and to 
assert their opposite. But we simply cannot conceive a world 
in which a thing is what it is not. And what is true here is 
true also of the other principles. We cannot deny them. We 
may adopt, of course, the agnostic's attitude and believe 
nothing. But though we should thus cease to tiffirm the prin- 
ciples, we should not be denying them. Moreover, this attitude 
is itself hardly possible. We know that the real does not con- 
tradict itself, and on this matter we cannot not believe. Yet we 
cannot give any reasoned ground for our belief if it were at 
all necessary. We believe because we know the real and arc 
convinced that we know. 

This is clearly an important matter, and we shall return to 
it later. In the meantime, it is obvious that if we have any 
knowledge at all of the real, we have it when we know the 
principles, and we shall proceed on this understanding. It is 
now, however, necessary to consider a further problem that 
arises in this connection. Arc we to regard this knowledge of 
principles as something unique? In particular, does it com- 
pletely differ in kind from the mediate knowledge which 
presupposes it? There will be no need to stress the prime 
importance of this problem for the present essay. 

Knowledge of the first principles, we have agreed, cannot 
themselves be known demonstratively. It was the recognition 
of this truth that first led to the explicit formulation of the 
distinction, which has since played an important part in 
cpistemological discussions, between mediate knowledge on 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 77 

the one hand, which involves a process, and immediate on 
the other. The knowledge of the principles must be of the 
latter type. It cannot be the product of any inferential process, 
for every process of inference is based upon it. So much is 
clear. But this whole distinction is frequently set forth as if 
there were two completely distinct kinds of knowledge, capable 
of functioning apart from and wholly independent of each 
other, and as if mediate and immediate knowledge were abso- 
lutely different in their nature. Now, is this view sound? If 
accepted, the complexities of the epistemologist's problems 
are so increased that it becomes wellnigh impossible for him 
to give a satisfactory and consistent account of knowing. 
This, however, should not restrain us from accepting the view, 
if we can prove it to be sound. But we can hardly claim that 
we are now in a position to offer any such proof. For, assuredly, 
before we can* assert with any show of authority that the 
knowledge involved in mediation is absolutely distinct from 
that of the first principles, our understanding of both kinds 
of knowing ought first to be intimate and thorough. But 
actually, while we have very little information as to the know- 
ledge of first principles, we have at the present stage even less 
with regard to mediation. Therefore, until fuller information 
is obtained, the absoluteness of the distinction remains simply 
a conjecture, premature and as yet unjustified, which the facts 
when revealed may wholly fail to warrant. 

Indeed, one interpretation of the distinction can easily be 
refuted on reflection. It may be said that the knowledge of 
the principles is unique (completely distinct from mediate 
knowledge) in the sheer purity of its intuition, an intuition 
which is so pure and so distinct that it needs an object which 
is itself distinct and purely simple. Now the raison d'etre of 
such an interpretation is not far to seek. So closely is object 
related to subject in knowledge that if we once conceive of 
the knowing as distinct and unique we tend naturally to think 
of its object as being so also. A unique act of knowing suggests 
an equally unique object. Furthermore, it may be argued that 
the uniqueness of the object is not only suggested but made 



78 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

necessary by the uniqueness of the knowing. For 'intuitive* 
knowing, it may be (and often has been) said, is unique in the 
sense that, unlike the laborious knowledge gained after long 
processes of reasoning, it takes in the whole truth at once; it 
'grasps' the complete real directly at one grasp (to use a 
physical analogy). But if this is so, then it seems to follow 
that the real or the true, the object in this case, must be that 
which can be so grasped. It must, that is to say, be something 
complete in itself, totally distinct from all else, an isolated 
and discrete unit. What is known must be pure in the sense 
that it is throughout one and the same; it must be simple, 
having no parts and no connections ; it must be a perfect unit 
which, being wholly independent of all else, is either known 
by this one act of apprehension or remains unknown for ever. 
Thus the exigencies of this view would compel us to see the 
ideal of all knowledge, the perfect example for* which we have 
sought, in a sheer intuition of sheer simples, an atomistic 
intuitionism. 1 

We shall devote the whole of the next chapter to a discussion 
of intuitive knowledge. In this section, all we wish to show 
with regard to it is that, whatever we assert about other 
cognitive experiences, knowledge of the first principles cannot 
be such sheer intuition of sheer simples. Against this position 
three objections might be urged. 

In the first place, it has been seen that the principles are 
simply so many pervasive features or characteristics of the 
real known by us. Now, clearly, a feature of anything cannot 
itself be described as 'a discrete and isolated unit' without 
talking nonsense. At most, such a description could only be 
applicable to that of which it is a feature. If the above argu- 
ment, therefore, demands a discrete unit as the object of the 
sheer intuition, then, obviously, knowledge of the principles 
could never be 'intuitive' in this sense. Consequently, the 
description a 'sheer intuition of sheer simples' cannot apply 
to our knowledge of the principles. We might, justifiably, 

1 The writings of Descartes provide us with an excellent example 
of this type of thinking; but it is in no way confined to his pages. 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 79 

advance this argument further. For if it be correct to hold 
that such principles are in truth pervasive and common 
features of all things real, then it seems to follow that there 
cannot be any real object which is a discrete unit or an isolated 
atom if, again, we mean by the latter an object different 
throughout from all other objects. For the real world, if the 
principles do hold of it, could never contain within it any 
object having no possible ground of relation with other 
objects, since the first principles would apply to each and 
every object, and so there would always be something in 
common. Such a discrete unit could only be an intellectual 
entity created by abstraction from the real (if, indeed, intellect 
could ever create a pure unrelated) ; and, therefore, in becoming 
aware of it we should not be knowing what really is. It also 
follows that the ideal of knowledge can never be a sheer 
intuition of she^r simples in the above sense, since knowledge 
is of the real, and all real objects must, at least, be related in 
this respect, and have this much in common, that the first 
universal principles hold of them. 

In the second place, our knowledge of the principles makes 
further knowledge possible. But an immediate apprehension 
of a purely discrete unit could never help us in our knowing, 
for though many such discretes were apprehended, no further 
knowledge could ever be drawn from them by any process of 
thought, and this because knowledge of a discrete unit could 
never tell us anything of the world beyond it. A pure discrete, 
that is to say, can never serve as a logical starting-point. 
Consequently, if knowledge of the principles were a sheer 
intuition of completely isolated discretes, then such knowledge 
could never play the supremely important part epistemolo- 
gically which our knowledge of the principles actually does 
play. It could supply neither the logical basis nor the guidance 
necessary for discursive thought. On the other hand, if our 
knowledge of the principles does supply the required basis, 
then obviously it cannot be an intuition of sheer discretes. 

Thirdly, however and this is the most important objection 
we have to make the position may be criticized on the 



8o THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

ground that it already isolates the knowledge of principles 
from mediate knowledge. For the implication of the theory 
under discussion is that the first apprehension of principles 
used in reasoning functions apart altogether from the subse- 
quent reasoning and is wholly distinct from it. In the first 
place, it is implied, we gain knowledge of the principles 
intuitively, and then, in the second place, we draw our infer- 
ences and work to our conclusions. These two functions of 
the mind, it is supposed, are wholly distinct, though the 
second presupposes the first. This would mean that nowhere 
in the mediate process itself does knowledge of the principles 
occur, but that it only occurs before the process begins, and, 
being in essence different from it, cannot occur as an integral 
feature of it. Yet actually any mediate process that we take 
into consideration reveals the presence in it of a knowing of 
principles. Each step in a valid mediate process can only be 
taken by a mind apprehending simultaneously the first prin- 
ciples. Thus in mediate processes the mind adopts one course' 
rather than another because it knows that, for example, a thing 
cannot possess two contradictory attributes and so contradict 
itself. Every movement in the process presupposes a present 
knowledge of these principles that is to say, of the funda- 
mental structure of the real. It is therefore absurd to suggest 
that the knowledge of the principles is not an integral part s of 
the knowing involved in mediation, since if it were not 
throughout present there would be no mediation whatsoever. 
Knowledge of the principles, therefore, is not something com- 
pletely distinct from discursive reasoning. On the contrary, it 
is itself a feature and a part of that reasoning, and without it 
the reasoning could not occur. 

Thus the knowledge of principles presupposed in mediation 
cannot be conceived as an intuition unique in character and 
differing absolutely from every other instance of knowing ; nor 
is its object a mere isolated and discrete unit. If this were its 
real character, mediation could not possibly presuppose it. 
We should not, of course, deny that the knowing of the first 
principles is 'intuitive' in the sense of being direct or imme- 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 81 

diate. We consider the description 'a direct and immediate 
knowledge or apprehension of the real' an excellent one in 
this context. What we should seriously question, however, is 
the implication that the same description cannot be applied to 
other instances of knowing, particularly to the knowing present 
in discursive reasoning. Indeed, so far as we can see at the 
present moment, the real difference between the knowing of 
principles and that which occurs in and through discursive 
reasoning may be external to the actual knowing itself, which 
as such may be one and the same in both these cognitive 
experiences. It is certainly not permissible to argue that since 
the knowledge of the principles is logically prior to any know- 
ledge that comes discursively it must be essentially different 
from it qua knowing. 

Mediation then, we can now say, presupposes as a wholly 
necessary precondition a knowledge, in the first place, of exist- 
ence a knowledge, as we contend, present in the lowest 
forms of the sensory experience and in the second place, of 
the general structure of that existence. The necessary priority 
of the latter, however, we must hasten to add, is logical, not 
chronological. For it is false to suppose that knowledge of the 
principles comes first in time and is isolated from the know- 
ledge present in mediation. On the contrary, knowledge of 
the principles, we have seen, is an essential part of the knowing 
in mediation, though we are not at present exactly aware of 
how great a part. It is evident, however, that it cannot be the 
whole of the knowledge therein contained, since in mediation 
we claim to know more than the mere general structure of 
what is, whereas knowledge of the principles provides us simply 
with this bare general structure. 

To conclude : though we do not understand as yet the exact 
place of this prior knowledge in mediation, we have learnt 
enough about it to enable us to assert without fear of refutation 
that the knowledge of the principles cannot be regarded as an 
'intuition' or direct apprehension, distinct from all other kinds 
of knowing, and having a distinct object. On the contrary, 
knowledge of the principles is so intimately related to the 



82 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

mediation which presupposes it that it cannot be considered 
as an instance of an isolated knowing complete in itself. Though 
it itself is clearly not the product of any mediate process, it is 
nevertheless embedded in processes of mediation. And before 
we can understand its nature we must learn more as to the 
meaning of the whole mediate process and as to the way in 
which greater knowledge results from it. 



The 'Experience' Presupposed 

All discursive reasoning, we have urged, presupposes a 
knowledge of the principles. Does it presuppose any further 
knowledge? Obviously, it presupposes something further 
(whether this be knowledge or not), since we could not pro- 
ceed very far discursively if we were completely confined at- 
the outset to a knowledge of bare first principles. The latter 
is certainly a condition sine qua non of all sound argument; 
but it does not provide premisses for any particular piece of 
reasoning. We must begin our process of discursive reasoning 
with definite information of some sort that may serve as 
premisses for our argument. But how do we gain this informa- 
tion? It is customary to answer that the content upon which 
and about which we reason is provided us in * experience'. 
Now this ans\ver needs to be examined further, for as it stands 
many different interpretations of it are possible. 

It is first necessary to set forth and criticize one interpreta- 
tion which we believe to be fundamentally unsound, in spite 
of the fact that, in some form or other, it appears frequently 
in philosophical speculation. For it may be said that if expe- 
rience does 'give' the content, then it cannot be the task of 
discursive reasoning to 'give' it over again. If we already know 
the content by way of * experience', then clearly we do not 
need to re-know the same content by way of reasoning. The 
view, of course, tacitly assumes that 'experience' and 'dis- 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 83 

cursive reasoning* are fundamentally distinct faculties of the 
mind having different functions, and since it is the function 
of the former to stock the mind with information about the 
real, it cannot also be the function of the latter. As a conse- 
quence, discursive reasoning as apart from 'experiencing* 
cannot, strictly speaking, be a knowing. It becomes for such 
thinkers something else, namely, a doing. In discursive reason- 
ing we do something with the content already known. 

The doing is a conceiving of concepts, whose necessity 
becomes obvious on a moment's reflection. For 'experience', 
on the present view, is supposed to provide us directly with 
knowledge of different particulars as they exist in the sup- 
posedly real world. But a world of particulars, owing to its 
endless complexity, is difficult to handle. Therefore, the task 
of reasoning is to conceive and use concepts or universals, 
each of which s l cands for a bundle of particulars. By this means 
the knowledge we already possess becomes easier to retain, to 
apply, and to communicate. Concepts are shorthand notes that 
save an immense amount of intellectual labour on our part. 
But their conceiving is clearly not a knowing on this view, 
even though we grant that greater knowledge may result after 
conceiving them because of the real economy secured and 
because the mind is then left freer than it would otherwise be. 
Also, conceptualizing enables the mind to bring many par- 
ticulars together, so that it can provide itself with a more 
comprehensive view of the real known by experience. Yet the 
conceptualizing itself is a doing here, and not a knowing. The 
concept is created, not known. Moreover, it is created in order 
to be used. We group together a bundle of particulars, agree 
upon a common name for the bundle, and so facilitate future 
reference to any particular within this group or class. But we 
do not increase our knowledge of the real in any way. At the 
most, what is additional is the name. All we know about the 
real, however, is already given in 'experience' before the con- 
ceptualizing begins. 

Such nominalism as is here set forth is no new doctrine. 
But, lately, it has taken upon itself a new form the economic 



84 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

theory of the concept. This theory concerns itself more par- 
ticularly with scientific thinking, one instance of discursive 
reasoning. 1 It is held, explicitly or implicitly, in some form 
or other for it appears in many guises by a large number 
of philosophers and scientists. It is the ground for much of the 
anti-intellectualism prevalent in Europe and America during 
the present century. And since it is so important, we shall 
devote the rest of this section to a critical examination of it. 
Here, again, we do not intend to adopt the historical method, 
but shall content ourselves with a statement of the theory in 
its most explicit form and with an attempted criticism showing 
both its strength and its weakness. 

Scientific thinking, the theory holds, is in essence practical, 
both in itself and in its purpose. It is the creating of a concept 
for use. The discursive thinking which is scientific reasoning 
gives us and can give us no new knowledge. Any further 
knowledge over and above the beginnings 'given' in experience 
must be expected not from scientific reasoning but from the 
use of another faculty. Thus, some who adopt the present 
view declare that an 'intuition' of living reality can take place 
in which no reasoning occurs, and that our hope of pure 
knowledge lies in this 'intuition'. Others assert that within 
'reasoning' in its widest sense we have also to include the 
pure knowledge of real being, as depicted, for instance, in 
Reason's knowledge of the pure concepts or categories. 3 But 
while a door is thus left open for the entrance of pure 
knowledge, both schools reject the view that science is pure 
knowledge. Science can only give us the pseudo-concept or 
artificial creation made for use and for use alone. In scientific 
reasoning the mind 'conceptualizes' or 'intellectualizes' the 
content given by experience, solidifying the flow of the real, 

1 It is not the only instance, obviously, if we mean by 'science', as 
is usual to-day, the mathematical description of nature. Philosophical 
thinking is another instance of discursive reasoning; for example, the 
reasoning about moral, epistemological, and ontological problems. 

2 The two schools we have more particularly in mind, of course, 
are the Bergsonian and the Italian Idealist respectively. 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 85 

breaking it up into bits and pieces and disregarding the 
differentia of each particular as compared with any other 
within a species. It does this because a 'conceptualized' or 
'intellectualized' content can more readily and more adequately 
satisfy the demands made upon it by the mind (which needs 
must use its knowledge) than can an 'unintellectualized' 
content. The aim of scientific reasoning is not the gaining of 
new knowledge. Its real purpose is to secure an easier applica- 
tion and a more efficient use of the knowledge we already 
possess; we can do more with 'conceptualized' knowledge than 
with that which is not 'conceptualized'. 

Now this theory, we readily admit, is a very important 
contribution to epistemology. It stresses the modern tendency, 
prevalent even amongst scientists themselves, to doubt the 
absoluteness of the results of scientific inquiry. It takes this 
tendency to its extreme and denies science all cognitive value. 
At the same time, however, it recognizes its supreme economic 
value. No instrument has ever served mankind better. But the 
value of such reasoning, the theory asserts, is practical rather 
than theoretical. The real knowledge in so far as there is 
real knowledge has already occurred before we begin to be 
scientific. 1 The scientific concepts are economic 'goods', made 
to be used. They must not be conceived as providing truth. 
They exist in order to serve a practical purpose. Science does 
not give truth: it controls nature. If we desire knowledge of 
reality we must seek for it elsewhere. 

In fairness to such thinkers, however, we must here note a 
further point. Their position cannot be identified with the 
Pragmatic school of thinkers who teach that knowledge itself 
is wholly utilitarian (or pragmatic) in character. Knowledge, 
the latter would assert, is merely 'what works'. It is completely 
subservient to action and is determined by our practical needs. 
Whatever best suits our convenience at any moment, that, for 
the time being, is knowledge. Now the theorists whom we are 
at present considering do not hold this view r . Some of them 

1 As one exponent of the view neatly asserts : Science is fructifcra, 
but not lucifera. Its soul is utility. 



86 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

would most emphatically reject it. Knowledge for them is not 
merely 'what works'. It may prove to help us practically in a 
particular case; in another it may not. Its utility is merely an 
accidental quality of it. Their real point, however, is that 
scientific reasoning is definitely and essentially utilitarian, 
definitely a doing and not an instance of knowing in any sense. 
The conceptualistic process is simply an economy. Its aim is 
not to know but to save mental labour. The most we can say 
for it is that it seeks to make greater knowledge possible, but 
we are never to say that it of itself knows. 

This doctrine is in certain important respects sound. It sets 
forward explicitly one feature of scientific reasoning which 
needed recognition and emphasis. Beyond a doubt such 
reasoning is a labour-saving device. The concepts that it uses 
have a practical value. They are often enough simply 'ordering 
conceptions' which help the scientist as he struggles to control 
nature. 1 To conceive them in themselves would not be to know 
the real. Undoubtedly, again, the scientist does not concern 
himself with, does not seek to know, many real details which 
could, he thinks, prove of no value to him. He ignores them. 
He is compelled to select. Science is certainly an economy, 
and, as such, considering only this side of its nature, it cannot 
be described as a knowing. So much seems true. In the next 
section we shall suggest that some such doctrine as this must 
be true not only of scientific reasoning, but of all mediation 
and of all discursive thinking. It invariably involves an element 
which is merely a doing. 

Yet, though there is obviously an element of truth in this 
doctrine, we nevertheless believe that, as it stands, it is 
unsound. As an account of scientific reasoning, taken as a 
whole, it leaves too much unsaid. It emphasizes one feature 
only, and consequently fails to present a true view of the 
whole. Scientific reasoning is admittedly an economizing, but, 

1 The history of science gives us many examples of 'ordering 
conceptions', some of which have long since been discarded. Such 
are, for instance, the concepts of caloric and ether which dominated 
eighteenth-century scientific reasoning. 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 87 

as we hope to show, it is also a knowing. And we cannot 
describe it fully unless we recognize the presence of this 
additional feature. For, like the sensory experience, scientific 
reasoning also, we shall contend, is a cognitive experience, 
even though there be that within it which is non-cognitive 
in character. 

By w r ay of preparation for the fuller description of discursive 
reasoning which we hope to proffer in the next section, we 
may here consider in greater detail the practical or economic 
feature of scientific reasoning. We shall also show how impos- 
sible the position becomes if we think of scientific reasoning 
merely in terms of this one feature of it. 

We may begin by pointing out that the economy under 
consideration can be secured in, at least, two ways: firstly, by 
arranging and ordering the knowledge we already possess in 
such a manner as to facilitate access to it; secondly, by learning 
how to deal with and how to control that of which we are 
partially ignorant. The second process enables us to act upon 
an object without first gaining full and adequate knowledge 
of it. It is clearly the more difficult task and demands the 
greater ingenuity. 

The first is a feature of thought everywhere. Indeed, the 
classifying and grouping, the ordering and systematizing, 
which provide formal logic with much of its subject-matter, 
may, from this point of view, be regarded as the effort present 
in all thought to lessen the mind's labours by presenting it 
with a connected system of knowledge. If there were no such 
systematizing in thought, the mind would always be faced 
with the completest disorder. Its knowledge would be heaped 
up in a chaotic mass, so chaotic that it could prove of little 
use in everyday life. Thought, as being an organizing and 
ordering activity, is that which safeguards the mind from a 
danger which is for ever threatening it, namely, that the 
knowledge it already possesses may become so inaccessible as 
to be worthless for all practical purposes. To avoid this the 
mind thinks in an orderly fashion (tabulating according to 
its concepts of species, genus, class, particular, universal, 



88 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

individual, and so on), in order that it may be enabled to 
make as full a use of such knowledge as it possibly can. 

This, therefore, is the first type of economizing connected 
with scientific thought. Now clearly, in such a case, thinking 
is not merely a doing. It is also a knowing. With each step 
forward in the work of systematizing and ordering we gain new 
knowledge of what can and of what cannot be linked together 
and related. We recognize, to say the least, in the present 
experience some feature or features common to many past 
experiences. We apprehend an identity, an apprehension which 
is definitely something cognitive. Moreover, our general divi- 
sions and systematizings (according to which we classify this 
present particular under its universal) would be valueless from 
a practical point of view if they were merely arbitrary. We 
must 'divide at the joints', and this implies that we know 
where the joints are. The doing in this case rrtast at one and 
the same time be a knowing if it is to achieve its purpose. 
And to repeat a tautology it must be a knowing of the real ; 
that is, of the world within which and upon which we act. 
Hence, to emphasize the very real economic value of such a 
systematizing process is a necessity, for it does present us with 
an orderly rather than a disorderly world, and so retains as 
accessible Avhat might otherwise become inaccessible. But this 
does not justify the further assertion that the process is purely 
a doing. For knowing, as we have shown, is inevitably a part 
of it, and, indeed, the main problems connected with it are 
essentially theoretical. 

But, perhaps, we are overthrowing a mere man of straw. 
For those who teach the economic doctrine of the concept 
might themselves readily admit that the particular kind of 
doing now under consideration must be accompanied Jby a 
knowing if it is to occur at all. Yet this, they might argue, is 
not the doing which is par excellence scientific reasoning. The 
latter is a doing of quite a different order, and is in no way a 
knowing. The concept (or pseudo-concept) of science, they 
might say, remains as yet wholly unconsidered by us. For it is 
not a feature of, or, again, a division in, reality. It is a symbol 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 89 

(for something in reality) used by the mind when it reasons 
scientifically. The scientist, they say, usually supposes, rightly 
or wrongly, that reality consists of individual things which 
affect us in the sensory experience. He also believes that the 
real individual is not revealed immediately and completely in 
sense-experience. For instance, he would be more ready to 
believe that the table upon which I write is an entity, con- 
sisting of a very great number of atoms, somehow knit together, 
than that it is the solid, unbroken piece of matter about whose 
existence the crude sensationalist would feel so confident. 
None the less, he finds in the sensory experience an invaluable 
aid from a practical point of view. For in it there recur often 
with great frequency certain regularities which he notes, and 
in time he is led to assume that such regularities are universal 
throughout sense-experience and will invariably recur in his 
own history afcd in that of other people. On this assumption 
he acts, and frequently his future experiences do justify his 
first assumptions, giving him a greater confidence in them. 
He seeks for more recurrences of the same type, his method 
being that of abstraction. He explicitly disregards all that is 
unique and does not recur. 

How, then, according to these theories, does he form his 
concepts? They are already being formed. He now combines 
together certain of these recurring features which have always 
gdne together in his experience, and to this combination he 
gives a name. This is his concept, an entity which, of course, 
does not exist apart from his conceiving of it. Is it not obvious, 
they would now ask, that when he does so conceive he knows 
nothing? For if he knew, he would know the real; but the real 
is the concrete individual, and not this collection of more or 
less regular recurrences. For all practical purposes and the 
view presupposes that the scientist's purposes are wholly 
practical it is sufficient for him to conceive his concept, a 
symbol of the real which helps him to handle it. He need not 
know the real, and, strictly speaking, never endeavours to do so. 
His concept is a general symbol for many real individuals, 
and the unique features, the idiosyncrasies of the latter are 



90 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

wholly left out of account. They are differentia which do not 
matter for the scientist's present purpose. 

Moreover, by reasoning conceptually, and not about each 
individual as such, he is able to make a fuller use of the 
ordering and classifying which is also part of scientific method. 
For the unique, which defies classification, is disregarded by 
the scientist. A botanist, for instance, when enjoying a per- 
ceptual experience, which we call 'seeing a particular butter- 
cup', recognizes what he sees as an instance of the species 
Buttercup, a concept with which he is already w r ell acquainted. 
But this again, he recollects, is a member of an equally familiar 
genus, Ranunculus. Consequently, by recognizing it as an 
instance of this species and genus, he indirectly learns a great 
deal which would help him to deal with this individual butter- 
cup, though he knows next to nothing of it itself. When the 
scientist conceives Ranunculus, he is, speaking strictly, knowing 
no real existence, according to these theorists. The real exist- 
ence is the individual buttercup; Ranunculus is a concept I 
have conceived. Yet such concept-making enables me to deal 
with the real things, namely, these individual buttercups, in a 
way that would be otherwise impossible in the circumstances. 

But the method permits of a much more extensive use. 
Thought's capacity for systematizing and ordering, its practice 
of setting out in compartments and of 'pigeon-holing', may 
further enable it to connect a concept with a whole order or 
system of concepts having its own formulae or conceptual 
abridgements of long processes of reasoning. Thus, when 
seeking to determine and to define certain variations in physical 
phenomena, we may observe that the changes under con- 
sideration always occur according to an order which we have 
met with elsewhere for example, in mathematics. Having 
observed this, we may endeavour to work out our problem 
mathematically, making as much use as possible of the formula; 
which are the stock-in-trade of every mathematician. In this 
manner we may quickly and easily gain precise results, whereas, 
if we had continued to search for them by observing the 
changes in the physical world alone, much greater mental 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 91 

labour and energy would have been necessary, while perhaps 
the actual result gained would not have been so complete. 
Such an application of mathematics to physics occurs more 
and more frequently. 

But the important point to note in this connection, our 
theorists would say, is that no new knowledge has been gained. 
Our doing gives no knowledge of the real, but it determines 
it conceptually in such a way that we can act upon it efficiently. 
The subject-matter of the scientist's thinking is the concept, 
and never the real individual, if there be such. For it is only 
when dealing with conceptual symbols of the real that he can 
make use of the formulae belonging to a particular system of 
concepts. The formulae cannot apply to the real individual as 
it is, different from all else. Hence it follows that, however 
successful the scientist be when using this method, he never 
comes to the knowledge of the individual as such by its means. 
That is not the purpose of the symbolization. Yet, without 
coming to know the individual thing in itself, the symbolization 
through concepts enables him to 'handle' such an individual 
much more successfully than he would otherwise be able to do. 
If, therefore, we expected from science knowledge of the real 
individual thing, our expectations could never be fulfilled; 
for from the moment we begin to be scientific we are no 
longer dealing with the individual thing as it is in its full 
reality. 

Taking all these facts into consideration, the theorist feels 
himself justified in concluding that scientific thought should 
no longer be conceived as a knowing. We do not know the 
real through such thinking; we merely learn how to handle it. 
'Conceptualizing' is never as such concerned with knowing 
reality. It is explicitly an economy. When conceptualizing we 
do not know anything fresh, but create (with the help of past 
knowledge) and make use of the concept. In science, such 
theorists contend, we sacrifice exact knowledge in order to 
satisfy our more immediate need for action and to secure 
control at the earliest possible moment over the forces of 
nature. It is for this reason that we bring into being and con- 



92 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

ceivc an unreal, split-up, 'pigeon-holed*, but more tractable 
world. 

Now, how far is the position here outlined correct ? We have 
already seen that the success of scientific reasoning in ordering 
and classifying its content is itself sufficient proof of its more 
comprehensive knowledge of the real. What of the scientific 
concept? Are we, in conceiving, also knowing (even though 
our primary purpose is practical)? Or is it merely a doing? 
That the first alternative in this case is the sounder in spite of 
the above theorists is suggested by the fact that purposive 
acting in adult human behaviour, such as the scientist's, 
invariably implies knowing, and that, therefore, if through 
scientific reasoning increased action becomes possible, this in 
itself is a sure sign of an increase in knowledge also. It is 
quite true that we may and continually do act on things 
without knowing everything about them, yet the surest way 
to secure a more efficient control over anything is to increase 
the sum-total of our knowledge about that thing. For how 
could a mere * conceptualizing', that never sought to know the 
unknown, help us to 'work' more satisfactorily on the unknown ? 
It clearly could not. The hard-and-fast distinction between 
'doing' and 'knowing' is illusory. Every doing is in part a 
knowing; all human action is that of a knowing mind. The 
absolute distinction thus glibly pre-supposed by adherents of 
the economic theory of the concept is artificial in the extreme. 
To uphold it is to do an injustice to the facts of human expe- 
rience. Acting implies knowledge throughout. 

At present, however, \ve need not follow out this line of 
criticism. Such generalities as these arc apt to produce vague- 
ness and indefiniteness, whereas, in this case at least, a clearer 
and more apt criticism is at hand. For, according to the theory, 
the concept is made for use. Yet once the position is fairly 
understood, it is difficult to see how such a 'creation' could 
ever be of any use. Instead of aiding the mind in its dealings 
with the real, it itself cannot but mislead it on every possible 
occasion. For, on this view, the real is unlike the 'conceptual 
stuff' created by the scientists. The real is not split-up and 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 93 

'pigeon-holed' into distinct compartments. It is only our 
failing intellects that need the 'split-up* conception of it. It is 
we who solidify the ceaseless flow of real life and create the 
concept by cutting out a piece of the mass thus solidified and 
giving it a name. This unreal symbol of the real we preserve 
and communicate for our use. But surely, on the face of it, 
there is something absurd in the position. If I ever did make 
use of these unreals, how could I hope thereby to deal more 
effectively with the real? How can I, carrying on processes 
of reflecting about a split-up world, hope to handle the real 
life-flow more successfully? Would not such 'conceptualizing' 
decrease rather than increase my power of acting on the real ? 
Would not such a creation be valueless or even definitely 
harmful? The only conceivable manner in which the 'creation* 
could be of real use would be as turned back again into the 
fluid mass. The concept made for use, that is to say, is useless 
until we know or perceive that moment of the flowing reality, 
as it actually is, for which the concept stands and of which 
it is the solidification. Otherwise, it misleads the mind, 
causing it to believe, for instance, that it has to deal with 
solid lumps of stuff, rather than with a ceaselessly flowing 
real. 

But, again, supposing it were possible for the mind to 
recollect, with the aid of the concept, that aspect of reality 
which it solidifies, this recollection, on the view under con- 
sideration, would prove equally valueless. For the ever- 
changing real would have taken upon itself in the meantime 
a new aspect, and we should therefore recollect what had 
already become unreal. That is to say, to act on the real world 
at any particular moment we must have knowledge of the 
real as it is at that moment. And this is true whatever view we 
adopt as to the nature of the real, whether it be a ceaseless 
flow, or a block universe, or anything else we choose. If the 
concept fails to provide such knowledge, it is worse than useless. 
Conceptualizing must be itself a knowing ; it cannot be merely 
a doing of something with knowledge gained beforehand. For 
if we find it easier to act on the real as the result of a con- 



94 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

ceptual process, our increased facility of action must be due 
to the fact that the conceptual process has itself increased our 
knowledge of that real. 

As it stands, therefore, we cannot accept the economic 
theory of the concept. So long as it contents itself with 
describing scientific reasoning in terms of 'doing' only, its 
description must remain inadequate. For the practical success 
resultant upon such reasoning is in itself a sign that new 
knowledge of the real is being gained in the process. We may 
certainly use symbols to help us. Also we have a right to guess 
at the truth when we do not know it, and even to assume 
certain things to be true for practical purposes and for the 
time being. We have never denied this. Certainly, again, 
scientific reasoning is an 'economizing', and to think of it as 
such is to gain a better understanding of its nature. But if no 
more be said the description is totally inadequate, and, as such, 
falls away from the truth. 

All such description is misleading not because scientific 
reasoning is affirmed to be a doing, but because it is affirmed 
to be merely a doing. The suggestion that a process of scientific 
reasoning nowhere involves as an essential feature of it a 
knowing cannot stand examination. Knowing, we contend, is 
part of the inmost structure of that intellectual activity termed 
scientific reasoning. Furthermore, and this is the most impor- 
tant point of criticism we wish to make, the denial of this 
assertion would have been wholly impossible were it not that 
a serious error had crept into speculations about the intellect's 
work. We refer to the erroneous supposition with which we 
began this section, namely, that a stock of knowledge lies 
ready to hand in the mind, and that then thought or reasoning, 
or, again, intellect, begins on its task of 'handling' the already 
known. 

This is an old fallacy. None the less, the new economic 
theory of the concept, as we have before suggested, is grounded 
upon it. For the position set forth above is but the modern 
counterpart of the nominalistic tendencies of past generations 
of philosophers. As such, we reject it. The intellectual process, 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 95 

if it involves a doing, is also at one and the same time a 
knowing; and while emphasis on the economic value of such 
a process is permissible and necessary, no true view of its 
nature can be attained unless equal emphasis is laid on the 
cognitive character of the process. 

If we now return to the problem with which \ve started 
this section, namely, the problem as to the legitimate use that 
may be made of the term 'experience', we may conclude that 
we must not speak of it as providing grist for the mill of 
intellect, stocking the mind with a knowledge-content in order 
that the intellect may work upon it, if by this it be also meant 
that the intellect itself need kno\v nothing further. This view 
of the relation of 'experience' and 'thought* is unsound, for, 
as we have shown, it is difficult to see how in these circum- 
stances what the intellect did with the knowledge given it 
could prove 01 the slightest value. But if this view is false, 
what is the true one? Is there a legitimate use of the term 
'experience 5 ? Can it ever mean something necessarily pre- 
supposed by a process of mediate thinking? These questions 
open up the whole problem of the true nature of mediation, 
and we can no longer evade a definite discussion of it. For no 
final solution of these preliminary problems concerning the 
presuppositions of mediation can be given until we solve the 
central problem, namely, "What does the phrase 'mediate 
knowledge' itself connote"? 



3 
The Nature of Mediate Knozvledge 

In this section we hope to gather up the strands of the 
preceding argument. Up to the present, our search for a 
perfect example of knowing has led us, firstly, to deny that 
seeing a colour, hearing a sound, and so on, is knowing; 
secondly, to assert that the sensory experience is nevertheless 
cognitive; thirdly, to reject the theory that the apprehension 



96 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

of the first principles (while it obviously is knowledge) is a 
knowledge of sheerly discrete simples; fourthly, to dispute 
the economic theory of the concept according to which con- 
ceiving is merely a 'doing'. But while we have succeeded in 
establishing these positions, it is obvious that the perfect 
example of knowledge for which we seek remains undis- 
covered. The sensory experience is a complex whole whose 
most characteristic part is non-cognitive. The knowledge of 
first principles is embedded in discursive reasoning, and is 
not in itself a whole concrete experience. Scientific reasoning, 
the one instance of discursive reasoning as yet considered by 
us, has revealed itself to be in part a 'doing', even though, as 
we contend, the 'doing' could not occur without a concomitant 
knowing. Nowhere have we discovered an experience which is 
through and through pure knowing. 

Nevertheless, each of these experiences is cognitive, even 
though none of them is wholly knowing, and in examining 
them we have already gathered certain facts about the cognitive 
experience in general. Thus we have agreed that the knowledge 
of principles is the immediate apprehension, present in dis- 
cursive reasoning, of certain universal characteristics possessed 
by the real. An active mind apprehends or grasps the real 
straightway. The analogy implied is, of course, that of physical 
grasping, as when I grasp a physical object. And though 
it does not follow that this analogy most appropriately 
expresses the real character of knowing in every other 
connection, it seems apt when applied to knowledge of the 
principles. 

But now the specific problem of the present section arises. 
For in outward appearance, at least, most of what we ordinarily 
suppose to be knowledge fails to conform with the above 
description. It is not direct, but indirect. Are there, then, two 
kinds of knowing, the one direct, an apprehending, and the 
other indirect, something different in kind? An affirmative 
answer seems to be inevitable, but we hesitate. For have we 
not seen that our best instance of immediate knowledge is 
itself somehow embedded in a process of discursive reasoning 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 97 

whereby we hope to gain knowledge indirectly or mediately? 1 
Can mediate knowledge, then, be immediate, even in part? 
Now a full and complete account of mediate knowledge would, 
no doubt, include a thorough-going logic of all inferential 
processes, both deductive and inductive. But such a logic 
would be beyond the scope of the present work. Instead, we 
shall confine ourselves to the consideration of two problems, 
whose solution ought to throw further light upon the nature 
of knowing. Firstly, what exactly do we mean when we talk 
of knowing mediately} And, secondly, how does this knowing 
compare with that which is immediate ? In answering the first 
question, of course, we shall have already, implicitly at least, 
answered the second. 

Our present problem, then, is to determine the nature of 
mediate knowledge and to distinguish it from immediate 
knowledge. And in order to make our position completely 
clear, we propose to put forward without further delay the 
main thesis of this section. We wish to argue that a hard-and- 
fast distinction between mediate and immediate knowledge, in 
which these are taken to be two distinct types of knowledge, 
cannot stand examination. Actually, all knowledge, wherever 
and whenever it occurs, is immediate in character; the facts, 
when considered, justify no other interpretation of them. 
Nevertheless, this statement is in no way incompatible with a 
continued use on our part of the term 'mediate knowledge', 
and we do not intend to dispense with the latter. For it 
expresses something which definitely needs to be expressed. 
The unfortunate fact is that when we analyse instances of 
* mediate knowledge' we find that the phrase carries with it 
two significations, and that neither of these significations can 
be disregarded. In the first place, we mean by it an immediate 
knowledge of an implication considered not so much in itself 
but with special reference to the light it throws upon the 
subject of the conclusion implied. As an illustration, we have 

1 For the present we use 'indirect' and 'mediate' as synonymous 
terms. What we mean to express by them will be further illustrated 
by examples in the pages that immediately follow. 

G 



g8 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

our mediate (or indirect) knowledge about S in a syllogism 
that it is P. We shall proceed to consider this instance in the 
next paragraph. In the second place, 'mediate knowledge' 
frequently connotes a complete thought-process culminating 
in a knowing (which is itself immediate) or in an opining. 1 
The knowing or opining becomes possible as the result of the 
process. To add to our difficulties, we also find that the phrase 
is habitually used to connote both significations at one and 
the same time, that frequently the culminating knowing or 
opining is itself of an implication. 

We must consider the matter in greater detail. A very good 
illustration of mediation is the perfect syllogism: M is P. 
This is the major term, in which we assert a universal truth 
or general principle. S is M our minor term, asserting a 
particular truth. There follows the conclusion , S is P. We do 
not know directly that S is P; we know it indirectly. We see 
that the premisses imply it. Now, how can w r e best describe 
the mediation present in this syllogism? It would obviously 
not be an adequate description of it to say that it is a sequence 
of three true judgements ; nor even a sequence of three judge- 
ments such that the final could not occur had not the first 
judgements preceded it. For though this latter might pass as 
a very superficial definition of syllogism, it does not set forth 
satisfactorily the inmost nature of the experience. It does^ not 
state positively that the final judgement is implied in the 
premisses, and it does not show the nature of its necessary 
derivation. The perfect syllogism, we should rather say, 
expresses verbally one whole movement of thought in which 
the premisses are seen necessarily to imply the conclusion. This 
statement, of course, is no definition of the syllogism as such, 
since it could be applied to any piece of sound inference, and 
not all inference is syllogistic. It is none the less valuable for 
our purpose, since it draws attention to the mediation present 
and seeks to describe it. The description is still superficial, as 
we hope to show. But it does bring out the first important 

1 In the latter case we have, strictly speaking, not 'mediate know- 
ledge', but an opinion arrived at mediately. 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 99 

consideration. Knowledge can occur mediately because we can 
see necessary implications. 

By this we mean that, granted a general rule of the type 
M is P, which must hold of all instances of M, and granted 
also that S is one instance of M, then this system of relations 
already implies that S is P. In other words, granted that some- 
thing can be predicated as holding of a general term, and 
also that S can be subsumed under this general term, then 
the predicate must equally apply to S. Now, if we analyse the 
above argument, it will be evident that it is based upon our 
knowledge of two relations, namely, the subject-attribute and 
the member-class relations. Our knowledge of the former 
alone makes possible the predication of M by P and S by M ; 
while that of the latter enables us to relate S and M. Our 
argurpent could not occur without a definite knowledge of 
these relations. Furthermore, we know that if M is P and 
S is M, then S is P. The sum of our knowledge, then, in the 
present case is that of the two relations, 1 together with the 
further knowledge that these relations under the conditions 
found in the demonstrative syllogism entail or imply a third 
relation. This third relation holds between S and P. No 
further knowledge is necessary to complete the syllogism. 

But we have said that the perfect syllogism is an excellent 
example of mediate knowledge. In what manner, then, does 
the* knowledge present in it differ from the immediate kind ? 
This is a difficult question to answer. For, firstly, knowledge 
of the above relations, subject-attribute, member-class, seems 
to be definitely immediate. It is a direct apprehension of 
objective relations. (Indeed, that these relations cannot them- 
selves be known syllogistically is obvious once we remember 
that knowledge of them is presupposed by all syllogism, and, 
in this respect, they are on the same footing as the co-called 
Laws of Thought. Like the latter, they are characteristics of 
reality that we must first (speaking logically) know if we are 

1 In order to avoid confusion, it is perhaps best to add that by 
these two relations we do not mean the two premisses. 



ioo THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

to syllogize about reality. 1 ) Nor, secondly, is the knowledge of 
the implication mediate. For we immediately see that if M is P, 
and S is M, then S must be P. But if this is all the knowledge 
that occurs in the syllogism, why call it mediate knowledge? 
The position seem?, to be that whenever we observe ourselves 
knowing, we find that our actual knowledge is immediate in 
character, whereas it is also clear that the syllogism as a whole 
is an instance of mediate knowledge. How can we overcome 
this seeming contradiction ? 

It cannot, if we are honest with ourselves, be overcome by 
supposing that knowledge of the implication is in some way 
not immediate. As far as we can see, it is so patently imme- 
diate that to suppose otherwise is really impossible. Conse- 
quently, we cannot agree that the actual knowing in the 
syllogism is itself a passage or a development from premisses 
to conclusion, and that in this sense only is it to be termed 
'mediate'. For this latter position seems to rest upon the 
erroneous assumption that the implication, the relation between 
premisses and conclusion, is itself the knowledge. Whereas it 
seems obvious that the actual knowing is not the implication 
as such, but rather our 'seeing' or our direct knowledge of this 
implication. Of course, it is the fact of implication which 
makes syllogism (and all inference) possible. We could not 
know the implication unless the premisses actually do imply 
the conclusion. But the implication, none the less, belongs to 
the objective rather than to the subjective side, to the known 
rather than to the knowing. In other words, however much 
the premisses imply the conclusion, no positive knowledge is 
gained until a mind, possessing the capacity to know, actually 
does know the implication. This is a fundamental fact; obvious 
perhaps, but yet dangerous to ignore, and fully worthy of our 
emphasis. For it makes it impossible for us to admit that 
syllogism and for that matter inference in general can be 

1 Whether knowledge of them is presupposed in all possible types 
of mediation or inference is, however, another question. Can we 
say, for instance, that the inference which is arithmetical calculation 
presupposes them ? 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 101 

rightly described as "the ideal self -development of an object". 1 
Mediate knowledge, we feel, is falsely conceived if it be 
conceived as a self-development. We readily admit that the 
conclusion of the syllogism is completely dependent on, 
wholly implied in, the premisses, but the knowledge which 
is present in the syllogism is o/this dependence or implication. 
It is in no way identical with the implication itself. Hence, 
we use loose and dangerous language if we say that the know- 
ledge present is the passage from premisses to conclusion, or 
is the development of the premisses into the conclusion. 
Actually, the knowledge which is the core of the syllogism 
is the immediate apprehension that the premisses imply the 
conclusion." 

We must, then, face the major difficulty. Viewed cognitivcly, 
the best possible instance of mediate knowledge, namely, the 
perfect syllogism, is essentially an act of immediate knowledge, 
however much it differ in certain respects from other instances 
of knowing. Syllogism most certainly cannot be regarded as 
the verbal expression of a type of knowledge distinct in kind 
from immediate knowledge. And what is here true of syllogism 
is surely true of all inference. What we describe as a process 
of coming to know X as the result of knowing Y, where Y is 
a premiss or a system of premisses, is really a seeing that Y 

' The phrase is Mr. Bradley 's. Cf. Logic, 2nd edit., p. 597. 

- In passing, we may add that the occurrence of syllogisms which 
are perfectly valid in spite of the fact that they start from false 
premisses in itself shows how the apprehension of the implication 
'$ the core of the syllogism. What we know categorically in syllogism 
r is such is the implication. Given the premisses, then we see imme- 
diately that the conclusion must follow. Moreover, because the 
knowledge of the implication is the essential element, we can quite 
legitimately syllogize even when we are not certain that P holds for 
ill M, or, again, that S is actually one instance of M. We can argue 
syllogistically to conclusions that are probable only, proceeding from 
premisses only probably true. But if our thinking is to be valid, we 
nust feel convinced beyond the possibility of doubt that the premisses 
io imply the conclusion. Here is the real knowing which occurs at 
the heart of the syllogism, and this, we argue, is immediate in 
;haractcr. 



102 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

implies X. What we call knowing X indirectly is really knowing 
directly that X is implied by the premiss or premisses. We 
know that S is P indirectly; and this means that we directly 
know it to be implied in the premisses M is P and S is M. 
That is to say, we know the conclusion hypothetically, // 
so-and-so, then so-and-so; but from the standpoint of the 
actual knowing this is merely to say that we know the impli- 
cation of the premisses categorically. No additional knowledge 
is involved. And the categorical knowledge in this case is 
direct apprehension. Hence, if what we say is sound, it follows 
that the difference between immediate and mediate knowledge 
cannot lie in the character of the actual knowing as such in 
both cases. The only observable difference at present is a 
difference caused by looking at one and the same thing from 
different points of view. We apprehend an implication directly, 
but by one and the same act learn something (indirectly) about 
the subject of the conclusion. Thus, though the actual know- 
ledge is immediate, we may mean by * mediate knowledge' th 
indirect knowledge we have about the subject of a conclusion, 
which conclusion we immediately see to be implied in certain 
premisses. 1 

But there is another sense in which we can talk of mediate 
knowledge, and the syllogism again illustrates this further 
sense. It is a sense of the term made possible by the fact that 
we frequently denote by the word 'knowledge' not only the 
act of knowing itself, but also a whole thought process within 
which such a knowing occurs. Consequently, while we continue 
to affirm that the actual knowing in the case of the syllogism 

1 Have we not here also the key to the understanding of the dis- 
tinction between the so-called 'knowledge by acquaintance* and 
'knowledge about'? Our suggestion is that all knowledge is actually 
'knowledge by acquaintance' if by this be meant what we have 
termed immediate knowledge or direct apprehension. But in the case 
of our 'acquaintance* with, or immediate knowledge of, an implica- 
tion we come to know, by this very act, something about the subject 
of the conclusion implied. 'Knowledge by acquaintance* and 'know- 
ledge about* arc one and the same thing looked at from different 
points of view. 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 103 

is no process from premiss to conclusion, but is the immediate 
apprehension of the implication, we can still admit that the 
knowing may result upon a process, and that the whole expe- 
rience might be conceived as 'mediate* in so far as the final 
knowledge comes about with the help of or through the whole 
process. 

But, if we use the term in this sense, we must bear two 
important facts in mind. Firstly, the actual knowing, the 
culmination of the process, is still immediate. Secondly, the 
mediation which occurs is not necessarily inferential. The 
first point we have already considered, but the second must 
now engage our attention. If we think of mediation as the 
process leading to knowledge, then inference is only one 
instance of such mediation and is not co-extensive with it in 
meaning. For we term 'mediate' here any process which helps 
us to know. 1 nus, for instance, the actual seeing of figures 
in geometry is a help in the gaining of knowledge. Yet we do 
not infer our knowledge from what we see. Again, the asking 
of certain questions and the clear formulation of problems, 
the gaining of new experiences, the recalling of truths (already 
learnt) at a certain point in the argument, the removal of 
prejudices these may all help to make knowing possible. 
For, on the one hand, they may clear hindrances out of the 
mind's path in knowing; on the other, they may so enrich 
the* mind as to enable it to know where it could not know 
before. In so far as they fulfil these functions, they are all 
instances of mediation in the broad sense now under con- 
sideration. Inference, however, is one particular instance of 
such mediation. Its distinguishing mark lies in the fact that it 
involves the apprehension of a necessary implication. Thus 
the syllogism is mediate knowledge in a double sense. It is 
mediate knowledge in the first sense in so far as it is indirect 
knowledge about the subject of a conclusion directly seen to 
be implied in certain premisses. But it is also mediate know- 
ledge in the second sense. For in it we find premisses set out 
by thought in such a manner that the mind can immediately 
perceive their implication, so that the relating of the premisses 



104 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

in this manner enables the mind to come to know an implica- 
tion, and, by one and the same knowing act, to know also 
something about the subject of the conclusion. 

But in whichever sense we use the word, in no case is 
'mediate knowledge' a distinct kind or type of knowledge 
standing over against the immediate kind. Its core, we repeat, 
is always immediate knowledge; in the case of inference, the 
immediate knowledge of an implication. It may be objected 
that such a view gives no room for certainty in the conclusion 
gained mediately. But this criticism could not be justified. 
What we do assert is that in syllogistic inference to revert 
to the instance of the syllogism we know directly the implica- 
tion alone, if M is P and S is M, then S is P. We do not know 
that S is P in itself, but only as implied in the premisses. 
We know it hypothetically, if ... then . . . We ask too much 
from the syllogism, as such, when we ask from it a categorical 
statement in its conclusion, for instance, S is P. All it can 
tell us with complete certainty is that S is P is necessarily 
implied in the premisses. If we do gain a knowledge that 
S is P which is certain in itself, categorically, then we do not 
gain it merely as the result of the syllogism. We admit that 
the knowledge of the conclusion in cases where the premisses 
are known to be true would be beyond doubt, but the con- 
clusion is not certain in itself; it is still certain hypothetically. 
It is certain because we know, firstly, that the premisses are 
true; secondly, that the premisses imply precisely this con- 
clusion and no other. We also admit that as the result of 
syllogizing we may become so familiar and so well acquainted 
with the character of S that by a direct act of knowing we 
'see' beyond all doubt that it must be P. That S is P would 
then become as completely self-evident to us as is the fact 
that the premisses imply the conclusion. But we should know 
that S is P in such a case not syllogistically but by a further 
act of direct knowing, for categorical knowledge of S that it 
is P cannot be given syllogistically as such. These, it seems to 
us, are the facts of the case. 

We ought to point out, however, before turning away from 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 105 

consideration of the syllogism, that usually we ask no more 
from it than probability. Most often, when we actually use 
syllogisms in reasoning, our major premiss is a memorized 
general rule of whose truth or falsehood we are not directly 
aware. Such, for instance, is the rule, all organisms are mortal, 
when we have not directly apprehended with apodeictic cer- 
tainty that mortality pertains essentially and so necessarily to 
organism as such. We have merely accepted the rule as some- 
thing generally assumed, and contradicted by nothing in our 
own experience, or, again, as 'proved' by us inductively. 
Now, in the syllogism, Man is an organism, an organism is 
mortal, therefore man is mortal; we make our appeal to this 
general rule as a major premiss. We do not directly see that 
mortality appertains to organism (for, in such a case, we 
should also directly see it to pertain to organism in this one 
instance of it, namely, man), but we have earlier established to 
our own satisfaction a general rule, and w r e now recall it and 
use it as our major premiss. We know with certainty that just 
these premisses imply this conclusion. And so, if our experience 
leads us to think these premisses on the whole sound, we think 
it safe to affirm the conclusion. Thus, though the syllogism 
in this, its more usual form, gives no theoretic certainty, none 
the less it gives probability. It is one method, of many used 
by mind, for bringing past experience to bear on present 
problems. When we fail to gain certain knowledge of X 
directly, we may yet arrive at probability if we can show that 
X belongs to a group each member of which, we have been 
led to believe in the past, is conditioned by a certain rule. In 
such a case, it is well to note, the probability is grounded upon 
a prior certainty, namely, the certainty that the premisses do 
imply the conclusion. 

Deductive inference, however (of which syllogism is one 
instance 1 ), is not the only type of inference, and we must 

1 We believe that our argument in the foregoing pages would hold 
for all instances of deductive inference, but to attempt a detailed 
proof in each instance would be too vast an undertaking for the 
present work. 



io6 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

now turn to consider the other main type. By inductive infer- 
ence we claim to know general laws not directly but mediately, 
proceeding from the careful observation of particulars. (There 
exists, however, one method of coming to know general laws 
which cannot be described as inductive, though it is tradi- 
tionally termed 'induction', and in this case we must not be 
misled by traditional terminology. The so-called Induction by 
Complete Enumeration, or Perfect Induction, is really non- 
inferential in character, that is to say, the final knowledge is 
gained directly. For if I actually see that so-and-so holds 
individually of each and every member of a class, then no 
inference obviously is involved in my asserting the universal 
application of the so-and-so throughout the class.) Where, 
then, shall we find inductive inference and inductive reasoning 
proper? Now, in spite of much disagreement amongst logicians 
as to the exact character of induction, there is general agree- 
ment as to the existence of a definite type of reasoning which 
is essentially inductive, and we propose to examine this 
reasoning briefly. The whole inductive process presents a two- 
fold character. The reasoning in it is carried on about certain 
alternatives already suggested to the mind by its observations. 
The first task in induction, therefore, is to set forth the alter- 
natives. These are hypotheses, possible general laws to account 
for the facts of experience. 1 For instance, we note that fre- 
quently two facts come in conjunction, and this suggests to* 
us their constant conjunction as a general empirical law. Or, 
again, we find one fact always preceded by another in such a 
way as to suggest that the first is the immediate cause of the 
second. In sound induction, of course, this work of making 
hypotheses is no mere guess-work. The hypotheses need to be 
well-founded. Incidentally, it is important to observe in this 
respect that in making the hypotheses we are guided not only 
by our present experience, but by much past experience 
relevant to the matter under consideration, as also by funda- 
mental laws or principles of thinking (both the particular 

1 We shall consider later in this section the meaning of the term 
'a fact of experience*. 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 107 

axioms of our particular science and the still more fundamental 
and pervasive Laws of Thought). 

Now observation of the facts usually suggests more than one 
possible general law, and we have to determine which law, 
amongst all the possible ones, actually holds in this case. 
This further task is carried out by a reasoning which is essen- 
tially inductive. It consists in eliminating hypothesis after 
hypothesis by the discovery of negative instances. Thus, if 
we make the hypothesis that X is the cause of Y, and discover 
an instance in which Y occurs in the absence of X, or fails to 
occur in the presence of X, then we can be certain that this 
one instance is sufficient to overthrow the hypothesis. In this 
manner hypothesis after hypothesis can be shown to be 
unsatisfactory, until, finally, one alone remain^ which still 
satisfies the facts. And since the facts must obey some law or 
other, we now conclude that the one remaining hypothesis is 
sound and states the general law. In other words, if the facts 
disprove every alternative except one, that alternative must 
be the right one, and we are justified in placing our faith in it. 
Such seems to be the core of the reasoning which is inductive. 
It has rightly been pointed out also that, even though we fail 
to reduce the number of hypotheses to one, something has 
been gained if we reduce them at all. Though still left with 
two alternatives, or even three, we are in a sounder position 
than when confronted with five or six. And if our partial 
reduction is carried out by the method of elimination, the 
argument remains definitely inductive. 1 

Here, therefore, is a further instance of mediate knowledge, 
and we have to ask of it the same question as was asked of the 
previous instance deductive inference. Is mediate knowledge 
here something completely distinct from immediate? Now in 

1 We have not considered here the methods of analogy and incom- 
plete enumeration which are usually classed with induction. In the 
former case, at least, it is exceedingly doubtful whether the argument 
can ever be based on any eliminative process as can the main type 
of inductive argument. These methods, however, have no great 
epistemological importance, and we need not consider them here. 



168 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

this case, again, we believe that a negative answer is the only 
possible one once we consider the position fairly. For if we 
consider inductive reasoning carefully enough, we must come 
to see that its essence or core is again the immediate appre- 
hension of an implication as something which is true in itself. 
We have satisfied ourselves that of certain laws suggested by 
the facts of experience, X alone holds throughout experience. 
(All other suggested laws have been contradicted by expe- 
rience.) Now we know that some law or other docs hold of 
experience. It is then obvious that X is the law which is valid 
for experience in this case. We see the implication directly. 
Our conclusion that X is the law is, ho\vever, gained infer- 
entially. The law, in so far as it is established inductively, is 
not self-evident. But the above implication is self-evident, and 
it is the implication that we directly perceive Of. apprehend. 
In knowing the implication \\ith certainty, however, we gain 
the assurance that X is the law which holds if our premisses 
are valid. In this sense our knowledge of the law is mediate. 
It is also mediate, we should add, in the second and broader 
sense. The whole process which is induction is, in part, a 
preparation for further knowledge, and the knowledge which 
finally occurs presupposes this preparation. The direct know- 
ledge of the implication, which, viewed from another angle, is 
indirect knowledge as to the validity of the law, can only occur, 
for instance, as a consequence of the right use of much we 
already know or opine. In reasoning inductively, for instance, 
we take it for granted that the world is uniformly ordered and 
not chaotic in its character, that it is intelligible; and we make 
use of this information. (To deny this, of course, would be to 
take away the very foundation of inductive reasoning. For, as 
we have shown, it is an argument carried out on the under- 
standing that some law docs hold for these facts under obser- 
vation, even if we cannot now exactly determine what law, 
and that if we succeed in setting forth all the possible alter- 
natives, then one of them must be the law which really docs 
hold.) Moreover, we have to search for hypotheses and elimi- 
nate those which are unsound, and this in turn is a task which 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 109 

presupposes the right use of much further information if these 
hypotheses are to be anything more than wild guesses. We shall 
presently return to the question of the part played by expe- 
rience in suggesting such alternatives. But the final conclusion, 
it is obvious, is reached through the use we make in a process 
of discursive reasoning of much prior knowledge, and is 
mediate, therefore, in this second sense of mediation. 

When we turn to consider the measure of certainty possessed 
by the conclusion of such an inductive process, we realize 
that induction, though it may give us practical assurance, can 
hardly provide theoretical certainty. We can never be wholly 
certain of our premisses. If our imagination were keener and 
more acute, experience might suggest to us still further alter- 
natives than those considered by us, and if we searched far 
enqugh we !jnght find a negative instance that would destroy 
even this hypothesis which we now accept as the true law. 
To derive a principle or law by inductive reasoning is most 
emphatically not to know it with certainty. 1 And yet, we may 
note in passing, general laws established in this manner con- 
stitute the large proportion of major premisses in syllogistic 
reasoning. But inductive reasoning, of itself, docs not culminate 
in the certain knowledge of a general law. For the most part, 
it enables us to make a judgement whose truth is probable. 
None the less, it may conceivably suggest a connection whose 
necessity w r e may come to see directly. It may fulfil the function 
of a propaedeutic to a future knowledge that shall be com- 
pletely certain even though it fail itself to give that knowledge. 
In such a case, we should know only in so far as we directly 
apprehend the necessary connection, but in suggesting this 

1 It is, of course, theoretically concehable that we should have, 
first, discovered every possible alternative, secondly, known that we 
had discovered all the alternatives, and, thirdly, shown all except 
one to be false. In this case we should have attained certainty, if the 
premisses were sound. Our assurance would still be of the hypothetical 
kind which pertains to whatever is known as implied. But actually 
inductive reasoning never gives certainty, since we can never be 
certain that every alternative has been considered nor that every 
negative instance has been brought forward. 



no THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

particular law and emphasizing its probable truth the induction 
would have helped materially. And even when induction fails 
to lead to such an act of direct apprehension, as is usually the 
case, its value still remains great. For, guided by 'experience' 
and past knowledge, it frequently gives probability of a very 
high order, and such probability is in itself extremely valuable; 
while, on the practical side, we continually act as if induction 
gave us not probability but certainty, and find the action, for 
the most part, successful. 

If we now reconsider the whole argument up to the present 
point, we see that the phrase 'mediate knowledge' is used to 
convey two distinguishable meanings. In the first place, it 
means indirect knowing that is to say, coming to know some- 
thing indirectly about the subject of the conclusion in seeing 
an implication directly. The latter is all the knowledge actually 
present. Simply as the result of our thinking, we do not know 
more of the conclusion than that we see it to be directly 
implied by the premisses. (Later, of course, by a further act 
of knowing, we may come to see directly the relation set forth 
in the conclusion.) There exists no indirect knowledge as 
something distinct and separate from direct knowledge. We 
cannot find any evidence of two distinct types of knowledge, 
the one direct and the other indirect, in this sense. Mediate 
knowledge qua indirect is simply the direct knowledge of an 
implication looked at from the point of view of the information 
given about the implied. But, in the second place, the phrase 
'mediate knowledge' also denotes a whole thought-process, 
together with the knowing that culminates it. Certain thought- 
processes possess just this characteristic that they culminate 
either in a direct apprehension or in an opining, and without 
the thought-process the apprehending or opining could not 
occur. (It is worth remembering, also, that a thought-process 
of this kind may frequently lead neither to knowledge nor to 
opinion, but to a state of suspended judgement.) Now the 
whole discursive-process, including its culmination, is an 
instance of mediate knowledge. If we think merely of the 
direct apprehension, however, in which the process may 



DISCURSIVE REASONING in 

culminate, we had best repeat that it itself is not a process. 
It is direct insight that comes like a flash after thinking about 
a matter, and so brings the thought-process to an end. Even 
in mediate knowledge it itself is immediate. 

We cannot, however, leave the matter of mediation thus, 
for though our main interest lies with the actual knowing and 
we have already shown what form it takes in inference yet 
a further question which arises in this connection must be 
faced. How can a process of discursive reasoning ever help us 
to know? To this question we should answer: Discursive 
reasoning facilitates the task of the knowing mind by pre- 
senting it, as the result of its thinking, with a world which is 
more systematic, more coherent, and within which a greater 
number of relations are already known. It can do this, we add, 
bepause it ^ses past knowledge and past opinions, and con- 
ceives its world accordingly. Now progress in knowledge is 
easier when dealing with the more ordered conceptual world 
than when dealing, for instance, with the sensory world. New 
relations are more easily apprehended. And often all advance 
becomes impossible until some further systematization is made. 

But, it will immediately be objected, the conceptual world 
is arbitrary, artificial, and unreal, the outcome of a falsifying 
abstraction. Therefore, conceiving can help us to know only 
in so far as the object we desire to know is unreal. It plainly 
cannot help us to know the real, for it hides that real from us. 
We, of course, do not agree. Conceiving helps to make greater 
knowledge of the real world the only knowledge we recog- 
nize possible. To understand how this comes about, we must 
first recall the argument of the previous chapter. The assump- 
tion underlying the above objection is that the real world is 
the sensory world, that the particulars of sense are the real 
things which exist, and that when we abstract in conceiving 
we are turning our backs upon the real world. But this assump- 
tion is totally false, and our theories as to the nature of con- 
ceiving, once the above assumption is made, cannot but be 
unsatisfactory in the extreme. For, if we once suppose that 
the only outlet to the real world is sensation, then clearly 



ii2 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

knowledge of that real for us must mean knowledge of this 
particular colour, this particular sound and taste. Anything 
else is phantasy. How far a perceived ' object' (not sensed as 
such) could be real would remain a difficult problem. But 
certainly a concept or general idea would only be possible as 
an arbitrary creation which itself could never be used to gain 
further knowledge. At best, it could only act as an economy, 
a 'shorthand-note'. For whatever we chose to do with our 
intellectual faculties, the real would always be known in 
sensation; and we could never 'abstract' from the sensory 
content without definitely moving away from the real; the 
image would have to be conceived as a weak or 'decayed' 
sensation; while the concept would be one stage further 
removed from reality. But when once we understand the true 
position, namely, that the content of sense is not itself the 
'stuff' of the physically real, we can then, at least, claim the 
right to abstract from its recurring manifold and to disregard 
certain details without necessarily suffering any loss in know- 
ledge of the objective reality. Once, then, we free our minds 
from false assumptions, there is nothing impossible in the 
suggestion that conceiving may help us to know the real. 
Some advance must be made on the sensible world. If we 
rest content with a world of sensible objects, which we too 
readily assume to be the real world, we shall gain no know- 
ledge. The first lesson we have to learn is that things do not 
possess just these sensory qualities which we ascribe to them 
in the sensory experience. The sensible world, which we 
naively claim to be physically real, is the outcome of our 
fundamentally false assumption that sensing is knowing with 
the consequent ascription of sensory qualities to that real. 
And we must first realize the possible falsity of this ascription 
before we can hope to understand how reasoning and reflection 
can enable us to gain, at least, probable truth about the world 
around us, and how they may lead to certainty. In spite of its 
conceptual character, the world conceived by the scientist may 
be more real (as, indeed, we usually believe) than is the sensory 
world of every-day. 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 113 

The above objection, therefore, cannot stand. That is to 
say, it cannot stand if we interpret it to mean that conceiving 
is no help in knowing the real because it (conceiving) itself is 
a turning away from the real revealed in sensory experience. 
None the less, we must admit that it has a certain force from 
another point of view. The objection may only mean that the 
conceptual world is in itself unreal (whatever the sensible 
world be), and so conceiving it cannot possibly help us to 
know the real. Here the objector would, at first, appear to 
stand on firmer ground. For it is hardly possible to deny that 
the conceived world about which we think is in part the 
creation of our own minds. In its totality it is not completely 
identical with the real world which we are coming to know 
through its aid. For instance, the man of science would be 
ready to admit that the world he presents to us was not wholly 
discovered by him. Quite explicitly, some of it is the fruit of 
his own imagination. But this admission cannot rightly be 
taken to prove the thesis that conceiving is of no help in 
knowing. For though conceiving is in part a creating, and 
though there is something arbitrary and artificial in it, we may 
yet claim for it that it makes more frequent advance in know- 
ledge possible. This advance becomes possible because in 
conceiving we abstract. We can (and do) select those elements 
in experience reflection upon which is most likely to lead to 
farther knowledge. Now the elements we do select are in- 
variably recurrent features. Through experience we become 
aware of certain common features features which repeat 
themselves on more than one occasion, and we frame our 
concepts according to these features. The existence of these 
common features is obviously important, since in reasoning 
we seek to link together and to systematize in the hope of 
coming to apprehend new links. But the completely unique 
would resist all our efforts at relating it with anything else. 
Therefore, we disregard what is unique in our sensory expe- 
rience. We disregard the particular time of the sensation which 
can never be repeated. We disregard the unique set of circum- 
stances in which the sensory experience occurred, but we 



ii4 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

fasten upon a feature, which this particular has in common 
with many others, and so link this particular up with other 
particulars, conceiving the type. 

But how does experience (by which we mean sensory expe- 
rience) 'give' us the recurrent feature? It would not give it if 
the sensory experience were merely a seeing of a colour, 
hearing of a sound, and so on. But the seeing of colours, as 
we have throughout insisted, is itself an occasion for know- 
ledge. When we see a patch of red, we spontaneously know 
existence. In seeing the colours, which are now before me, I 
know the difference between one and many. Moreover, I can 
pick out two that are like, and relate them as being like in 
colour. Now I do not see this likeness. I see the colours, but 
know the likeness. And it is our power of apprehending like- 
nesses in colour which alone enables us to conceive redness, 
blueness, and so on. It is not that all reds are identical in 
shade. It is questionable whether any two instances of red 
are even completely identical. Indeed, we conceive redness by 
arbitrarily taking one particular shade of red, not too dark 
and not too light, and making it stand for all others. (This is 
one instance of the 'doing' present in conceiving.) Yet we are 
only able to do this because we have apprehended a likeness 
and a similarity between different reds. The concept could 
not be made without the prior knowledge. It is based upon it. 
Sometimes, again, we come to know in experience not tne 
approximate recurrence of a colour, but the more exact recur- 
rence of a relation between colours for instance, a sequence. 
To take a simple case: In carrying out an experiment I see 
two colours, blue and red. I notice in carrying out many such 
experiments that the red always follows on the blue (this is a 
'fact* of my experience), and I conceive the event as a sequence 
of blue-red. 1 Now what happens here, speaking precisely, is 
this. I see the colours. I know the sequence, red following on 

1 To avoid, for the present, difficulties about memory, we may 
think of many experiments being carried out simultaneously before 
our eyes, so that we can see and compare them all at one and the 
same time. 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 115 

blue. Finally, I know that this sequence is repeated on each 
occasion. The last two items are definitely instances of know- 
ledge. That is to say, the feature apprehended as recurring 
was itself, in the first instance, known rather than seen, a 
known relation between colours. And it is not impossible by 
further abstraction to conceive the relation alone here 
sequence and to reflect upon it. But whether our concept 
be of this extremely abstract kind or not, the point we wish 
to make is that in forming it we are guided by knowledge 
already gained in sensory experience. Even though conceiving 
is, in part, creation, we neither create ex nihilo nor capriciously. 
The conceived world embodies in itself knowledge already 
gained, and the new ordering in conception proceeds according 
to what we know. Thus the more systematic character of the 
world conceived, for instance, by the botanist more syste- 
matic, that is to say, as compared with our own everyday 
non-scientific view of the plant world is ultimately based on 
his capacity to know real likenesses and is the consequence of 
his abstraction and selection according to this knowledge. All 
conceiving is ultimately based upon our knowledge of real 
features of that real world which we first know in sense- 
experience. 

We now begin to understand the role of experience in 
knowledge, and how discursive reasoning, through which this 
first minimum of knowledge becomes enlarged, most certainly 
presupposes it. Discursive reasoning is conceptual in character; 
but conceiving can only occur on the basis of what we already 
kno,w in experience. Conceiving is the outcome of abstracting 
certain real features known in experience in order to consider 
them alone and in order to pay greater attention to them. 
These features are also known to be common or universal 
throughout a particular group. Discursive reasoning is a further 
systematizing of these concepts according to what we know 
or opine. As such, it facilitates the task of the knowing mind, 
because the more closely knit, the more inter-related and 
connected, the world we think about, the more likely are we 
to see the necessity of new relations, or to opine that such- 



n6 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

and-such a relation probably holds of the real. And this con- 
ceived world, just as it is more systematic, is also more real 
than the sensory world, because in conceiving it we take up 
the knowledge already contained in the experiencing of that 
sensory world and increase it in our apprehension of new 
relations and of greater system. Thus the world conceived by 
the scientist, though not wholly real, is yet both more syste- 
matic in its character and better grounded than is the sensory 
world of the unreflective person. In other words, when 
reasoning conceptually, the conditions are more favourable 
for the occurrence of knowledge. Here lies the real utility of 
discursive reasoning from a cognitive point of view. It increases 
the possibility of further discovery. As such it has a side which 
is a doing. We readily recognize this. In inference, for instance, 
we must seek for, and bring together, the righ* premisses. 1 
Also the terms of the premisses are conceptual, and in thinking 
any concept we must bring many particulars under one head 
through knowing the recurrence of some feature. This bringing 
together, as such, is in both cases a doing. Yet it is a doing 
which proceeds strictly according to, and is justified by, a 
knowing (or an opining) of something in common between 
the particulars, and of something which can link the two 
premisses. And when this doing, so intimately bound up with 
knowing, has occurred, we may find ourselves in a position 
to gain greater knowledge, as when we are enabled to see 
directly that the premisses of an argument imply a further 
conclusion. 

And, perhaps, the true meaning of the second type of 
'mediation' considered by us in this section may now be 
more easily understood. It is mediation in this sense, that 
where we at first fail to know a truth, we may, as the result 
of discursive reasoning (or thinking), arrive at a position in 
which we can know it directly. Reasoning or thinking, from 
this point of view, in its systematizing and ordering, its 

1 This frequently involves the adoption of 'a trial and error* 
method of procedure. 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 117 

classifying and relating, is simply our effort to work ourselves 
into a position in which further knowledge can be gained. It 
is our effort so to enrich the mind or the intellect by a wise 
use of experience, of prior knowledge and opinion, that the 
mind is enabled to apprehend new truths. As such it is the 
process which makes the further knowledge possible. And 
mediate knowledge is this whole process completed in its 
culminating act the act of direct knowing. In other words, 
mediate knowing in this sense of it is in essence the appre- 
hension of a further truth through the use we succeed in 
making of past knowledge and of the whole experiences in 
which such knowledge occurred. Mediation is the process of 
using the knowledge and opinions we already possess in a 
certain definite manner, doing something with them, so as to 
gain still greater knowledge of the real, which new knowledge 
in its turn may be used again in the same manner. This is the 
true dialectic of knowledge. The final knowing, however (if 
knowing occurs), is not a doing, nor a process; in each case it 
is the immediate apprehension made possible by the process. 

With these statements in mind, we are better able to deter- 
mine the measure of truth which pertains to the economic 
theory of the concept considered in the last section. The 
concept, we can now agree, is, from one point of view, 'made 
for use'. But the use to which it is put is not the control of 
nature, as the theory supposes. It is only useful because con- 
ceptual reflection facilitates knowing, leads to further know- 
ledge. Its usefulness belongs primarily to the theoretical, 
rather than to the practical sphere; although, admittedly, the 
greater knowledge which it brings in its train may lead in turn 
to a greater control over nature. But conceiving is more 
immediately useful in so far as it helps to make possible 
further knowledge. And conceiving is useful in this sense, we 
argue, just because it is not merely a doing, but embodies 
within itself and applies to the present much past knowledge. 

It is necessary, however, to repeat that our discursive 
reasoning leads us most often not to certainty but to prob- 
ability. Occasionally, we are able directly to apprehend the 



ii8 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

truth as the outcome of the thought-process. But, usually, we 
do not enjoy such good fortune. The assertion of a probability 
is as far as we can get. But may it not be argued that the 
gaining of such a probability is itself a step forward in the 
process which brings us nearer the direct apprehension of the 
truth ? For the probable cannot be an end in itself. We cannot 
rest satisfied with it. Nor does our search end when we have 
attained it. It is true that in our practical life we only desire 
an effective control over nature, and if an estimation of the 
most probable gave us the desired control we should be 
satisfied with it. But it does not do so. Even in the practical 
sphere we need certainty; probability is only a makeshift. 
The doubt and uncertainty which are present in opining breed 
hesitation and awkwardness in action. And on the theoretical 
side it is obvious that the end of our inquiry //rust be .the 
attainment of certainty. Now, from this larger point of view, 
w r e may look upon any mediate process culminating in the 
attainment of the probable as itself a part of a larger process 
whose natural culmination would be complete certainty. In 
terming this larger process 'mediate' we might be stretching 
the word beyond its ordinary usage. But it would certainly 
be a mediate process in this sense, that through it an end 
would be attained, namely, certainty. Viewed thus, the attaining 
of probability would be part of a vast mediate process towards 
full and complete knowledge of the real. 

We may conclude the present section and chapter by sum- 
ming up the results of our inquiry as to the nature of mediate 
knowledge. We have seen that the evidence available does not 
justify the assumption of two completely distinct kinds of 
knowing, the one immediate, the other mediate. We have 
ample evidence of the existence of immediate knowledge ; we 
have none of the existence of a mediate knowledge distinct 
from it and opposed to it in character. It is not denied that 
X may be known indirectly or mediately. But this knowledge, 
on examination, reduces itself to a knowing directly that X is 
implied by certain premisses. The actual knowing present 
is direct, in spite of the fact that we talk loosely of knowing 



DISCURSIVE REASONING 119 

X indirectly. If we choose to maintain the term 'indirect 
knowledge* as meaning the (direct) knowledge of an implica- 
tion considered not so much in itself but according as it gives 
information about the implied, then no harm is done. 

The issue is complicated, however, by another fact. Knowing, 
frequently, cannot occur without a certain preparation in 
thought, which involves a right use of much past knowledge. 
First, certain conditions have to be satisfied. The act of 
knowing (or opining) presupposes a thought-process, fre- 
quently prolonged and intricate. This process also is rightly 
termed 'mediate', for through it we know, and without it we 
should not know; and there can, again, be no objection to 
this usage of the term, so long as it is understood that the 
knowing is the final act, the culmination of the process, but 
not. the pnx?ss itself. Search where we will, we cannot find 
any fair instance of a knowing which is a process. And until 
we find such an instance we cannot admit that it ever exists. 1 

There remains one final question. Can we claim to have 
discovered in discursive reasoning that perfect example for 
which we seek, that experience which is through and through 
knowing? Quite clearly we cannot. Knowing is invariably 
present in discursive reasoning, but does not exhaust its nature. 
In particular, that flash of illumination which occasionally 
brings the reasoning process to an end is certainly knowing. 
But it is never the whole of the experience. To consider it in 
itself, we have to abstract. None the less, we can claim to have 
learnt much in this chapter as to the nature of knowing, and 
as to the manner in which and the occasion upon which it 
functions within us. Mediate knowledge, we learn, is not 
completely and wholly different from immediate knowledge. 
On the contrary, the evidence seems to point to the fact that 
knowing is one in nature throughout. Throughout it is the 
immediate apprehension of the real. Differences between kinds 

1 In denying the position that knowing is a process we have, of 
course, in mind a logical process. From a purely psychological point 
of view knowing must be a temporal process, however short that 
process be. It takes up time. 



120 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

of knowing are really differences in the types of process which 
enable us to know, which liberate our capacity for knowledge. 
These differences form the subject-matter of logic. But the 
epistemologist and the metaphysician must concern themselves 
with the act of knowing itself, and must consider the difficult 
problem presented by the fact of knowledge. Whence comes 
this wonderful power, none the less wonderful in that it is 
meagre and limited in human minds? How can we explain 
knowing ? And what must be the nature of reality if within it 
there is a knowing mind? These questions, we believe, are as 
vital for philosophy to-day as they ever have been, and cannot 
be disregarded. In this essay, however, we mean to confine 
ourselves to description, and shall not attempt any explanatory 
answers. In a last chapter we shall try, by broadening our 
outlook, to complete this purely descriptive work/ 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 

THE argument of the earlier chapters points to the following 
position : the knowing act always remains identical in character 
however much the circumstances in which the knowing occurs 
may vary. Throughout, it is an immediate apprehension of the 
real. But is this position sound ? Is the knowing act one and the 
same throughout ? For even though we may now be prepared 
to accept the position with regard to the knowing present in 
the sensory experience and in discursive reasoning we may 
yet wish to make a reservation with regard to certain expe- 
riences which are abnormal but yet definitely cognitive. It 
is frequently assumed implicitly, and sometimes explicitly 
claimed, that there exist types of cognitive experience in which 
the actual knowing differs completely from, and definitely 
transcends, the knowing present in the sensory experience 
and in discursive reasoning, the ordinary knowledge of every- 
day. Clearly, if such types do exist, the above position cannot 
be sound. The knowing act cannot be one and the same through- 
out. The inquirer into the nature of knowing must therefore 
face this difficulty. And in the first section of the present chapter 
we propose briefly to consider some experiences which have 
been put forward as instances of 'transcendent' knowledge. 
The term 'intuition' is sometimes used in this connection and 
in* the second section we shall proceed to consider this term, 
and to give an account of the 'intuition' whose existence we 
feel it essential to posit in describing knowledge. 



' Transcendent* Knoivledge 

Pure knowledge, it may be urged, is enjoyed by few mortals. 
The realm of the mundane, where men grope about in darkness, 
can provide us with no instance of pure knowing. For, as it is 
in its purity, knowing does not belong to the everyday life 
of man; on the contrary, it is something 'other-worldly* and 



122 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

inspired, something foreign to man's natural estate. It may best 
be described as an intuiting. It is the vision of the poet, the 
illumination of the artist, the contemplation of the mystic, and 
the faith of the saint. It is knowledge of reality, not through 
slow and laborious processes of intellectual activity, but through 
an immediate and complete apprehension of what most truly 
is. Such knowledge does not belong to the common mass of 
men: genius alone enjoys it. The gap between it and those 
instances of knowledge which have thus far engaged our 
attention is as wide as that between the infinite and the finite, 
the perfect and the imperfect. 

This is the extreme form of a view which is hardly ever held 
by philosophers, but which is frequently found elsewhere. 
Ordinarily w r e do believe that the genius has his own way of 
knowing and that his way is not ours. Now yi seeking to 
examine this belief \ve meet, at the outset, with a very serious 
difficulty. To discuss the character of the 'transcendent' 
knowledge and to compare it with the rest of human knowledge 
we need first to have experienced it ourselves. Otherwise, we 
shall be discussing that of which we are ignorant. And if, in 
our ignorance, we make any assertions whatever as to the nature 
of such pure knowledge, the truly inspired person may speedily 
turn upon us and hold that our assertions are unsound and 
our account thoroughly false. Certainly, it is but natural that 
the vision of the greatest minds cannot be transmitted in its 
entirety to lesser minds. This is not because the vision is a 
mere subjective experience that cannot be shared ; nor because 
such men make any effort to keep the vision to themselves; 
but simply because other minds are not great enough to partake 
fully of that which the inspired person has to give. It is the 
mark of true genius that as one increases in appreciation of its 
productions and enters further into the mind of the artist, or the 
mystic, so one finds still greater depths unplumbed and new 
truths left undiscovered. And if such inspired men tell us that 
the insight they possess is something very different from 
discursive reasoning even at its best we have no right to 
disbelieve them. If the seer is convinced that the Spirit of Posey 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 123 

or of Painting has breathed upon him, or that he has been 
illumined by the Contemplation of the Light, or has himself 
taken part in the mystic dance around the Throne of God, 
trying thereby to express to us by metaphor what is otherwise 
wholly inexpressible in our everyday language, we must simply 
take it for granted that something has happened to him which 
does not happen to us. For this reason, what we have to suggest 
in this connection and throughout this section is very definitely 
tentative and uncertain in character, and we make no pretence 
either to a complete thoroughness or to an authoritative finality. 
We thus readily recognize that the vision of genius is far 
removed from the knowledge of every-day. We are anxious not 
to belittle the difference between them, for to do so would be 
to miss the real problem altogether. None the less, we cannot 
but feel that the view as set out above goes to too great extremes. 
A mysterious difference in kind is posited where there may 
after all be nothing but a difference in content known. Truly, 
the ordinary mortal cannot fully share in the inspiration of 
genius. But this fact in no way necessitates the belief that such 
inspired knowledge is totally distinct in kind from everyday 
knowledge. It may, of course, be so; yet it equally well may 
not. For it is surely illogical in the extreme to argue that since 
I know nothing of an experience it must be totally different in 
structure and kind from those experiences with which I am 
already familiar. Yet this seems to be the drift of the argument. 
Of this thing I know nothing; therefore, it must be completely 
and mysteriously different in its nature from everything I do 
know. But to think so is to think fallaciously. The unknown 
need be no more mysterious than the known. And in this case, 
we suggest the difference may be merely one of content. Does 
it not seem that the real ground for the distinction between 
'every-day* and 'transcendent' knowledge lies in the difference 
in nature between the object known in the two cases? It is, 
primarily, the fact that poet, saint, and mystic claim to 'draw 
down heaven', whilst the ordinary man in his ordinary mood 
does not lift his eyes above the world around him, that leads us 
to allot the term 'heavenly* to the knowledge of the former and 



i2 4 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

'earthly' to that of the latter. And it may yet prove that changes 
in content, the what known, need not involve a change in the 
knowing. One and the same power of apprehension may be 
capable of knowing both 'earthly' and 'heavenly'. In such a 
case, though what he knows is so very different, the actual 
knowing of the most inspired poet may be identical in nature 
with my own. 

But surely, it may be objected, that which knows the finite 
cannot also know the infinite? Yet this, perhaps, is what the 
objector too readily assumes. At least, he should first prove his 
thesis. For it is not inconceivable that the mundane and the 
transcendent, the extraneously conditioned and the absolute, the 
finite and the infinite may, in spite of all their difference, be 
apprehended by acts of apprehension identical in nature. 
The 'inspired' person certainly deals with quite a different 
objective world, and no doubt quite a different set of circum- 
stances may be necessary to enable him to know, yet it is not 
absolutely necessary that his knowing, as such, should differ* 
in ultimate nature from the knowing act involved in everyday 
knowledge. 

At the same time, admittedly, it is only too evident that if 
certain theories with regard to the nature and status of human 
knowledge were sound, the mind that knew the finite could 
certainly never succeed in knowing the infinite. As an instance 
one might take the theory which confines human knowledge 
strictly within the limits of the phenomenal and holds that 
valid knowledge is only possible for the human mind in so far 
as the mind itself sets out the principles which the world it 
knows obeys. It would then be clear that the transcendent 
could never be known by such a mind. To know the transcen- 
dent it would need a capacity and power wholly different in 
nature from that which functioned when it gained knowledge 
of the phenomenal world. Thus it would be necessary to assert 
the existence of two completely distinct kinds of knowledge ; 
the one knowing the phenomenal, the other the transcendent 
or ultimately real; the one, in part at least, a creation of its 
object, so that the object depends upon it for its very existence, 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 125 

the other a discovery of an independent object. But such a 
dualistic interpretation of knowledge is in no way necessary, 
we contend, if the description given in these pages is the true 
one. For we do not believe that human knowledge is ever of the 
phenomenal. No such distinction as that between the pheno- 
menal and the real needs to be introduced, on our view. Know- 
ledge, if it occurs at all whether it be at a high or a low stage 
of mental development is of the real. It is true that the mind 
conceives a world in imagination to aid it in its knowing; and 
certain of its principles are in reality only well-founded hypo- 
theses; but it does not then know the conceptual, it knows the 
real with its aid. 1 Wherever knowledge occurs, the object is the 
real. And, we add, the knowing act which enables us to know 
the real at the finite level may also quite conceivably know the 
real t;hat lies beyond it. 

> If we now take stock of our position, we can affirm, on the 
one hand, that the supreme knowledge of the 'inspired' person 
need not 'be totally different in kind from the knowledge of 
everyrday, even though its content differs exceedingly; and 
on the other, that the account of knowledge given in the earlier 
chapters of this essay may, in its general outlines, quite con- 
ceivably apply even to the 'transcendent' knowledge discussed 
in this section. We may, therefore, ask whether, as a matter of 

x * The only occasion upon which the mind can be said to know the 
conceptual is in self-consciousness. The mind turns back upon itself 
and observes its own conceptualizing. This is knowledge again of 
the real, but of a real which is subjective rather than objective. 
Incidentally, we may add, the argument of the previous pages also 
holds with respect to the subject's knowledge of itself. It is admittedly 
difficult to understand and to describe this knowledge. In particular, 
the fact that the subject known can never be an object of knowledge, 
since as such it would not be subject, seems to make the task of 
describing self-consciousness additionally difficult. But surely these 
facts do not make necessary the conclusion that the act of knowing 
involved in consciousness of the self is completely different from 
the act of knowing involved in all other cognitive experiences. And 
yet this belief is frequently found. We suggest that it is at least 
conceivable, and, as far as we can see, probable, that our actual 
knowing of the subject is identical in character with that of the object. 



26 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

r act, 'inspired' knowledge is of the same kind as the knowledge 
rf every-day, and whether the account given of the latter does 
not hold equally well of the former ? 

We propose to suggest that an affirmative answer ought to 
be returned here, that just as it is with everyday knowledge 
so with the knowledge of genius, first, there is an effort of some 
sort to enable him to know, and the knowledge itself which 
follows is an immediate apprehension of the real. For our 
information we have to rely largely upon that which the knower 
chooses to tell us and he, most frequently, is not very communi- 
cative on this point. Usually his mind is so full of the vision he 
has seen, and he is so anxious to share it with others, or at least 
to express it adequately, that he has very little time to spare 
in which to describe the manner of his coming to knowledge. 
For instance, it is but rarely that one finds a p^et discussing 
the exact nature of his insight. That is none of his business. 
He will be ready enough and anxious to present his reader with 
the truth he has discovered. He has learnt of life, and what he 
has learnt has so elevated his thoughts that he cannot contain 
his emotion but must express it, using in the expression the 
language natural to great emotional stress, namely, rhythm. 
But he does not reveal so readily his spiritual history from 
the point of view of his knowing. He has much to say of life, 
but very little of how he learnt all he now knows about life. 

The problem is further complicated by the fact that many 
poets from time to time have held a theory as to the nature 
of poetry which differs essentially from the one implied in the 
above paragraph. The poet, they w r ould say, does not, as a 
matter of fact, seek for truths at all. If he does so, then he is 
no longer a poet, but a philosopher or a scientist. The poet, as 
poet, is an artist and, like every other artist, his work is to 
amuse and to interest by doing something well though, of 
course, the amusement need not be frivolous in character. 
It is not his duty to seek new truths about life. His task is to 
create Beauty and not to discover Truth. There are thus (at 
least) two types of poets : the one strives to know and to reveal 
the inward truth of life and holds this to be the proper business 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 127 

of the poet, the other is content to amuse by using words in an 
exquisite manner. The latter type does not seek to know. 
The ordinary knowledge of every- day is sufficient for his 
purposes. His aim is to set it forth in a way that will please. 
His real interest is in technique and not in content. 1 

Fortunately, it is not necessary for us in this work to settle 
the issue as between the two schools. Our interest lies clearly 
in that type of poet for whom art involves, in part at least, the 
gaining of new knowledge. For the purposes of this argument, 
therefore, we may disregard the poet who is interested in 
technique and form alone. And of the other we shall ask, Is his 
knowledge different in kind from the knowledge of the scientist 
to take our best instance of * everyday knowledge'? How 
does the knowledge of the one compare with that of the other ? 

By way of Answer, we may at least point out certain details 
which appear to be analogous in the two cases. Both seek truth 
and both find hindrances in their path. We have already shown 
how a scientist finds it necessary to work mediately by way of 
discursive reasoning. It is by such laborious processes alone 
that his immediate apprehension of new truth becomes possible. 
So, too, the poet must struggle and strive if he is to gain a more 
comprehensive insight into the real. It is no easy, effortless 
acquisition. Biographies of this more romantic type of poet 
have constantly to mention severe and often bitter mental 
conflicts, from which relief is found in the actual composition, 
the expression in verse, when it becomes possible. Mental 
struggles of this kind with the passionate emotional outbursts 
that accompany them seem to be the inevitable counterpart of 
the more romantic poetic inspiration. Their source is a failure 
to 'gain the vision'. Truth does not flash upon the poet's mind 
spontaneously whenever he desires to understand. Poet and 
scientist are alike both in seeking for truth and in finding it 
only after much effort. 

They proceed to overthrow the obstacles in their path, 
however, in a different manner. The scientist proceeds logically. 

1 The difference here is, perhaps, exaggerated in order to make 
it clear. 



iz8 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

He reasons discursively, from one relation to another according 
to the Laws of Thought. He 'perceives' various implications 
and uses his knowledge to systematize his world as completely 
and as coherently as he possibly can. Consideration of this more 
systematic world enables him to apprehend new truths which 
in turn lead on to others. Now though the workings of the poet's 
mind remain largely a mystery, it is quite evident that he does 
not proceed in this manner. He does not stand aside to argue 
from one abstraction to another. Instead, he enters into the 
centre of the flood and seeks to live out as complete a life as 
is humanly possible. In imagination, at least, he will taste of 
all things, and as he tastes and lives he learns. Thus, a more 
or less permanent conflict within the one mind between 
two strands of temperament, between, for instance, an austere 
asceticism and an indulgent laxity, may of itself,Jead to many 
experiences which result in greater insight into the real. Out 
of the conflict, as a flash, a new truth about the life he lives 
comes to him, and it is this truth, now apprehended by him- 
for the first time, which he expresses in his poem, finding relief 
in the expression. Thus it is the living out of life either actually 
or in imagination which provides the medium through which 
the poet attains his knowledge. It is not by processes of discur- 
sive thought carried forward in a strictly logical fashion that he 
usually overcomes the hindrances. It is as if the power that he 
possesses of knowing lies captive within him until he experi- 
ences in hisown tense fashion thepleasures, the joys, the sorrows, 
and the griefs of life, its strain and its conflicts. To know he 
must first live intensely and imaginatively. This vivid imagina- 
tive experience seems to be the poet's mediation whereby he 
attains the end he has in view, namely, a fuller understanding 
of life. 1 

But does the poet really know? Or does he merely delude 

1 Incidentally, imagination is also an essential feature of scientific 
thinking, as we have shown. But, in science imagination is the hand- 
maiden of logic; in poetry, imagination as a means to an end, namely, 
the attainment of knowledge, is supreme. (I am, of course, thinking 
of the romantic type of poetry only.) 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 129 

himself in thinking so? To this question we can provide no 
definite answer, and that for reasons already touched upon. 
When it is asked, Did this thinker gain greater knowledge of 
the real through this particular piece of discursive reasoning? 
I can often answer, yes, or no. For, starting with the same 
premisses and carrying out the same process of reasoning, I 
myself come or do not come to the same conclusion. That a 
process of reasoning implies such and such a conclusion is 
something neither true nor false for me until I have 'seen' its 
truth (or falsity) for myself. But it is, to say the least, extremely 
difficult for the ordinary man to capture the poet's experiences 
in order to verify his conclusions. Yet until he does so he can 
neither confirm nor reject that which the poet claims to be true. 
Of course, the information may be such that it can also be gained 
through a process of discursive reasoning, and in this case I 
could verify the poet's assertions without entering into his 
experiences. But when this is not possible I am powerless to 
pass judgement. 

Byt the matter goes deeper. If it be ever true that the poet 
does arrive at knowledge independently (either wholly or in 
part) of logical processes of discursive reasoning, this would 
mean that the real may on occasion be known by a method 
that for want of a better name we shall call 'non-logical 1 . 
In such a case, knowledge of the real would not be the monopoly 
of scientific thought nor even of the discursive process. Logical 
reasoning 1 would not always be necessary for knowledge. Is 
such a view sound or false ? Is a logically disciplined process of 
reasoning essential for the occurrence of knowledge? Or has 
the poet his own method of attaining to truth? The evidence 
points to the truth of the latter alternative, but one cannot 
commit oneself until much further consideration has been 
given to the matter. The whole problem is obviously one of 
extreme importance. 3 

1 We do not say Reason, which may mean something very different, 
namely, that which we here refer to as the 'knowing act*. 

3 Our knowledge of the principles presupposed in reasoning is an 
excellent instance of knowledge gained prior (logically) to all processes 

I 



tao THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

But though we cannot answer definitely, our account of know- 
ing would not be proved invalid if the above view were sound. 
In particular, we could still assert the identity of the knowing 
act itself throughout all cognitive experiences. For in any pro- 
cess of discursive reasoning, as we have described it, the know- 
ing act is a distinguishable feature within the whole of the 
experience. It is not the whole of it. And the fact that the 
poetic experience qua cognitive differed from discursive 
reasoning would not necessitate the existence of two completely 
distinct acts of knowing. The knowing act itself might be 
identical in character within both experiences although the 
circumstances necessary for knowledge in each case differed 
completely. This would suffice to make them radically different, 
and we do not wish to minimize that difference. But 
in such a case the difference would lie not so -much in the 
knowing itself, as it actually occurred, but in the prior efforts, 
whereby the mind succeeded in working itself into a favourable 
position for knowledge. To conclude, then, whether we speak 
of poet or scientist, we can say that each possesses power to 
know, but that this power lies in bondage and needs to be 
freed before the act of knowing can occur. The freeing takes 
different forms, the objects known may also differ exceedingly, 
but the knowing act, that flash of illumination, when it occurs, 
seems to be identical in both cases, and there is nothing in our 
general account of knowledge up to the present which makes it 
impossible or even difficult for us to believe this. 

We are now in a position to give some sort of answer how- 
ever hesitating to the question with which we began this 
section. Is there a 'transcendent' knowledge wholly distinct 
from the everyday knowledge of ordinary life ? We answer that, 
confining our remarks to poetry, the knowledge which the poet 
claims to gain differs in objective content from the knowledge 
of every-day ; that, furthermore, it also differs on the subjective 

of reasoning. So that it would be patently false to assert that all 
human knowing occurs as the result of discursive reasoning. The 
present question, however, is: Has the poet discovered a method of 
procedure ', which is non-logical and yet leads to knowledge? 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 131 

side, since in the poet's experience the power to know which 
he possesses is liberated and given freedom to operate in a 
manner that is, perhaps, uniquely his; but that the knowing 
act itself thus liberated does not, so far as we can see, differ in 
the two cases. The 'heavenly' knowledge of the poet is, in its 
essential character as knowing, in no way different from the 
'mundane' knowledge of the scientist and the ordinary man. 
Regarded from the point of view of its content it may be fuller 
and more perfect, as the poets themselves would claim, but 
from the point of view of the knowing act involved and of its 
functioning, it seems to be identical in nature with the types 
of knowledge discussed earlier. Such is the suggestion we make. 
We have no space left in which to consider other branches 
of art, such as painting, music, sculpture, and so on. 1 Nor can 
we discuss jiere another type of knowledge, which may be 
regarded as 'transcendent' in character, namely, that which 
makes possible the moral life. Perhaps, in no sphere are there 
problems so difficult of solution as those which face the moral 
philosopher, and, at the present stage, we prefer not to venture 
any opinion whatever with regard to them. We may, however, 
justifiably point out what is, indeed, common knowledge, that 
the moral life is not achieved easily. Here again a struggle is 
involved a struggle, moreover, w r hich is two-sided. For 
while it is no easy matter to know what path we ought to tread, 
it* is even more difficult to tread it in actual practice. From the 
point of view of an epistemological inquiry, of course, the 
gaining of new moral knowledge would be the more interesting 
feature, though no doubt the effort at living out what one per- 
ceives to be the good life would itself lead to a deepening of 
our knowledge and could not be ignored. Further, the impera- 
tive which commands us unconditionally to do that which we 

1 It may be objected that in taking the case of the poet whose 
purpose it is to gain knowledge we have not really been dealing with 
an artist at all, since it can never be the purpose of an artist, as 
artist, to gain knowledge. If this be true, we agree that the instance 
taken is unsatisfactory: But, on that hypothesis, the consideration of 
art would not come within the scope of this essay. 



i 3 2 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

determine to be the right thing in the circumstances would 
itself need examination. With regard to the gaining of new moral 
knowledge, however, we should be tempted to say that moral 
knowledge is a direct apprehension of truth, though an act of 
apprehension w r hich could not occur without, and except 
through, the prior occurrence of certain auxiliary processes 
which make the apprehension possible. What these processes 
are we do not here profess to explain. 1 

Finally, to consider the matter of 'transcendent* knowledge 
adequately, we should have to devote very serious attention 
to religious knowledge and to faith. Now in so far as we use 
this latter term to express a kind of knowledge, we may mean 
by it one of two things. In the first place, little more may be 
meant than hearsay knowledge, as when one knows a matter 
not through finding it out for oneself, but by hearing about it. 
(Most of our everyday 'knowledge' is of this kind.) Thus by 
faith is often meant simply the acceptance of the dogmas 
taught by some religious body or other dogmas which pro- 
fess to be truths gained earlier in the history of that religious 
body. Of course, if the acceptance is sincere and not merely 
nominal, faith, even in this sense, does involve some measure 
of finding out for oneself. The sincere believer does not blindly 
swallow everything offered him. In the last resort, he can accept 
nothing which openly conflicts with his own experience and 
thinking. He does accept a position without having discovered 
the full truth about it for himself; nevertheless, as much truth 
as he has discovered seems, taken all-in-all, to point to the 
truth of this position. In such a case faith is the theoretical 
counterpart of trust. When I say I have 'faith* in a person or 
'faith' in some project my use of the word implies that I do not 
know for certain at the time how this person will act in the 
future, or whether the project will turn out in the hoped-for 
manner. But my knowledge of the person, and again of the 
project, is sufficient to make me feel fairly confident as to the 

1 Where we fail to gain complete certainty on a moral issue, we 
may either gain a measure of probability or suspend our judgement 
entirely. 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 133 

issue, and though I have no certain knowledge I have 'faith'. 
No doubt, much religious 'faith' is of this kind, and for beings 
who are not omniscient (but who have yet to live and to act) 
such 'faith' is a necessity. We accept on hearsay a dogma and 
believe in it because it confirms our knowledge and our own 
experiences and even explains them. What we know in no 
way establishes the dogma's validity; but it points the way of 
the dogma; and so we accept the latter though we ourselves 
did not discover it for ourselves but learnt it from another. 
Frequently, we mean no more by faith than this acceptance on 
our part of another's discovery in the religious sphere. 

In the second place, however, we may mean by faith the 
first apprehension of such dogmas, the 'inspired' knowledge of 
religious genius. Such knowledge, it is only too clear, differs 
radically in <*ne important respect from the knowledge of every- 
day things. When I know the material world around me I 
know it, we usually imagine, by my own efforts. In such a case, 
we should not ordinarily say that the object known helps me to 
kno\y. When, however, I know some other mind the object 
here may help me to know. I know more about my friend than 
I do about a perfect stranger, and this because my friend has 
in part 'revealed' himself to me. The object known has helped 
the subject to know. Now in the case of religious knowledge 
the object is God, Omniscient and Most Perfect. Hence, if 
man learns of God it can only be because God Himself imparts 
the information. Knowledge of God cannot be conceived as 
something which we ourselves discover by our own unaided 
efforts. On the contrary, we naturally feel that if we know Him 
at all, it must be because He himself has chosen to reveal 
Himself to us. Man's knowledge of God must be revelation; 
in it God Himself discloses to man His own nature. The term 
'revelation' should be retained. It aptly describes this most 
characteristic feature of man's religious knowledge. Yet, grant- 
ing that here the subject-object relation is of a unique kind, 
there is still no necessity to suppose that the actual knowing is 
different in character from all other instances, for it is quite 
conceivable that God might choose to reveal Himself to us by 



134 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

way of the ordinary channels of knowledge. Our knowledge 
in this instance may proceed in a fashion identical with all other 
knowledge, the only difference being that we cannot suppose 
this knowledge could ever occur were it not God's will that it 
should. But is faith, then, as the religious genius's knowledge 
of God, actually identical in nature with other kinds of 
knowledge, or is it distinct in kind? 1 

Again, we can only suggest the possibility of an affirmative 
answer. In the first place, the prior struggle which we have 
come to expect is obviously present. However strong and pure 
be man's desire to know Him, God does not quickly reveal 
Himself. The greatest religious teachers that humanity has 
known all unite in this testimony that God is to be found only 
by dint of ceaseless search. And, certainly, few ideas show 
slower development historically than does the idea of God. If 
God is to be known at all, He cannot be known in any effortless 
way. First there must come, as a necessary precondition, a 
process in all cases arduous and prolonged in which the 
mind is prepared for the knowledge of God. What everyone 
would wish for, if he once thought it possible, namely, the 
immediate attainment here and now of a complete knowledge 
of God, is, as a matter of fact, wholly impossible. The religious 
genius gains his insight into God's nature gradually. Always, 
so it would seem, there must be a preparation of some sort 
through which alone that insight can become possible. 

But in what does the preparation consist ? Do we seek Him 
through the medium of logically constructed processes of 
thought, or through our imaginative and emotional experiences ? 
Clearly both media have been used. Philosopher and poet have 
each sought for God in each his own way, and on occasion both 
claim to find Him ; while, often enough, since there is something 
both of the poet and philosopher in every man, the two methods 
have been combined. The mediation, that is to say, is not 

1 Throughout the above paragraph I have been following so closely 
upon Professor C. C. J. Webb's argument on this matter which 
seems to me very sound that I must here be allowed to acknowledge 
the debt. 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 135 

invariably 'logical' in our sense nor invariably imaginative, but 
may be either or both. Nor are these the only ways of approach. 
On the contrary, it would seem as if every path that leads to 
knowledge, of whatever kind, can be utilized in the search for 
God. 1 

In the second place, the experience would be impossible had 
we not power to know, and were not this power actualized, 
in the experience. For though we admit the uniqueness of this 
instance of knowledge and recognize in it God's revelation of 
Himself to man, nevertheless man must be capable of receiving 
the information imparted to him, he must himself possess the 
power of apprehending the Object. After appropriate prepara- 
tion the knowledge comes like a flash to the active mind. 
Religious knowledge cannot be a passive experience. Revelation 
is only pos^ble in so far as man possesses power to know and 
to apprehend. Thus, though the faith of the saint, as a cognitive 
experience, may differ greatly from our ordinary everyday 
knowledge, there nevertheless pertain to it certain general 
characteristics which belong to human knowledge in every 
sphere. Through some process or other a capacity is liberated, 
what is potential within us is actualized, so that we attain 
knowledge of the Object. 

All mystic literature is a constant re-emphasis of this truth. 
Every man, whatsoever his estate and condition, possesses 
within him potentially the knowledge of God. The Light is 
within, even though at present it be enshrouded in darkness. 
Consequently, the mystic consciously sets himself the task of 
actualizing the potential. He seeks a Way, whereby he may 
attain the fullest experiences possible. Firstly, he holds, there 
must be a purifying, a moral disciplining, a giving up of the 
'life of the flesh'. Secondly, Wisdom must be diligently pur- 
sued. Not only must the 'flesh' be conquered, but one's place 
in life must be learnt. This understanding of life is gained in 
many ways. It may be gained by way of science and philosophy, 

1 Frequently enough, for instance, a fuller consciousness of the 
moral life and of its demands has led to an increased knowledge 
and understanding of God. 



i 3 6 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

or by way of religious devotion, or by the contemplation of the 
beautiful, or even, lastly, by faithful and long-sustained service 
to one's fellow-man. By such moral disciplining and by such 
acquisition of Wisdom the soul of man is prepared for the 
beatific vision of God. If the Way be truly and faithfully 
followed, then gradually our faculties will be freed, the obstruc- 
tions which encompass the Light within will be removed, and 
the highest knowledge together with the noblest emotions will 
be ours. 1 

At this stage the knowing act within will be freed completely. 
Its final emancipation will have occurred. In such a case, if 
we know at all, it will be with God's knowledge, which differs 
from finite knowledge in that nothing ever hinders its function- 
ing. At the finite level it is only with difficulty that we can 
conceive of such an experience and we cannot foel sure that 
'knowledge' is the right term to apply to it. Yet implicit in the 
position of these mystics is the belief that, in the last resort, 
our knowledge is not completely different from God's. The 
Light within each soul is already something divine. The know- 
ing act itself, it is implied, is infinite. It is its opposite, that 
which hinders its operation and that which we must first over- 
come and remove if we wish to know it is this, which is finite 
in the cognitive experience. God's knowledge, on this view, 
actually is what our knowledge would be if the power to know 
within us were liberated not spasmodically, here and there, 
but everywhere and in every circumstance. 

But, at present, we do not wish to follow out this extremely 
speculative line of thought. Our task is a humbler one. As the 
conclusion of our reflections in this section we are not able to 

1 It is necessary, however, to note one important modification. 
The mystical consummation of man's experience, the last stage of 
all, is not the mere knowledge of God. Higher than knowledge of God 
is unity with Him. When both the intellect and the emotions of man 
are developed to their uttermost, then, at such transcendent moments, 
one's self will be merged within the Divine. One's will, one's thought, 
one's emotion so the mystics claim become God's; though, indeed, 
it may very well happen that we ought no longer to speak of will, 
thought, and emotion in this context. 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 137 

offer any demonstrated facts. We can only make a suggestion, 
which seems to us to be truer in this connection than any other, 
namely, that the highest cognitive experiences of which man is 
capable are not altogether different in nature from our more 
ordinary cognitive experiences. They share many character- 
istics in common with the latter. The mystic's striving through 
years of patient labour for a completer insight into the Divine; 
Nature, the storm within the artist's mind before the vision 
flashes upon him, the conflict of desires and the * inward argu- 
ment' which precedes the intuitive apprehension of one's 
obligation and duty is there not here something analogous 
to the intellectual struggle, the mediation presupposed by each 
new act of knowing in the sphere of discursive reasoning? 
And does not the analogy hold, we suggest, because in their 
ultimate nature all these experiences are one and the same? 
They are all finite cognitive experiences, that is to say, experi- 
ences in which the mind, already possessing the power to know, 
can nevertheless only know in certain definite conditions which 
must first be secured. Now, if this suggestion is sound, then 
the 'transcendent' knowledge of inspired genius does not differ 
fundamentally and in kind from the 'mundane' knowledge of 
the ordinary man. Genius, in all these manifestations of it, 
seems to be the consequence of a better use of one's faculties, 
resulting in a more complete liberation of mind than is usual. 
fjut these faculties do not belong to genius alone, they are 
latent in all of us. The inspired person follows a path that all 
may follow, and that everyone, indeed, actually does follow 
whenever he succeeds in gaining new knowledge by whatever 
method. 

Thus, as we see it, there is no greater mystery in the know- 
ledge of the genius than in the knowledge of any one of us. 
The real mystery is the act of knowing itself if that which 
is so natural to us as to be, perhaps, what we most essentially 
are can actually be termed 'mysterious'. If it were possible to 
explain this act of knowing, the core of all our cognitive experi- 
ences, the further difficulty as to the nature of the higher 
knowledge of inspired men could hardly prove insurmountable. 



i 3 8 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

The real problem for the epistemologist, who seeks not only 
to describe but also to explain, is to discover the source of 
the mind's cognitive power, which is as clearly present in the 
everyday knowledge of the man in the street as in the superb 
vision of genius. From this point of view, the lowest type of 
knowledge is no less remarkable as a phenomenon, even though 
( it emerge in those experiences which we share with the beasts 
of the field, and even though all the information it has to give 
is of some drab corner of the world around us. 



The Intuitive Character of the Knowing Act 

* 
In this section we propose to argue that the knowing act is 

intuitive in character. On our view, no other term more 
adequately expresses the characteristic nature of the knowing 
act whenever and wherever it occurs. But if we use the adjec- 
tive we must make clear what we mean and what we do not 
mean by it. For a loose use of the term is dangerous. There 
is a healthy tendency nowadays in philosophical circles to 
deprecate the over-frequent usage of the term 'intuition'. Too 
often in the past its use has conferred an appearance of wisdom 
upon what is actually loose thinking, and on many an occasio'n 
it has served as a cloak to hide real failure. It is, assuredly, 
one of the easiest terms to misuse; and, whenever it appears, 
one should be on one's guard against the intellectual laziness 
of which it is a frequent sign. For the term readily lends itself 
to false usage. This is, perhaps, due to the fact that by an 
'intuition* we frequently mean an experience which we have or 
do not have, but which is not further analysable into anything 
other than it itself. Consequently, simply to avoid greater 
mental effort, a lazy thinker will be tempted to call every 
experience, which he finds difficult to analyse, 'intuitive'. The 
inevitable result is that the term has become suspect. 

Nevertheless, we consider the use of the term justified in thq 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 139 

case of the knowing act. The knowing act is an intuition. 
This does not mean, however, that the whole cognitive experi- 
ence is through and through intuitive; for the knowing act is 
not the whole but a part only of that experience. The fact is 
that we have failed to find an instance of the perfect knowledge 
for which we seek in this essay, an experience through and 
through knowing and nothing else. None the less, we have, 
discovered true instances of knowing, and we claim for each 
instance that it is intuitive in character, though the knowing 
in each case is only a part of a larger experience. This is obvi- 
ously true of our everyday experiences. And it seems equally 
true of any higher experiences we might enjoy. For even 
though we were to admit that the genius enjoys supreme mo- 
ments in which the mind is, as we say (speaking loosely), filled 
with illumination or inspiration, yet such moments are essenti- 
ally parts and parts only of knowing experiences, and each 
part is dependent upon the rest of the experience to which it 
belongs. The moment of complete insight is the consummation 
of a whole experience, and is only isolated from it by a definite 
act of abstraction. Though we recognize the presence of real 
differences, both objective and subjective, between 'transcen- 
dent* and 'every-day' cognitive experiences, these differences 
are yet not sufficient to destroy the general identity of character 
which, so we argue, persists throughout these experiences. 
In the two groups, the whole cognitive experience is a process 
involving the liberation of the knowing function on the one 
hand, and its actual functioning on the other. Now this func- 
tioning, this act of knowing, seems to be identical throughout ; 
and throughout it is intuitive in character. 

Moreover, we should say that the knowing act is the sole 
intuition. By this we mean that it alone satisfies our notion of 
what an intuition should be. It is direct and immediate know- 
ledge. Its object is the real, not a representation nor a copy of 
it. It is no process, but is an act of apprehending and this, 
though we admit that whenever we find it it is embedded in a 
process. It is mi generis, like nothing other than it itself. It is a 
unique form of mental functioning, and, finally, it is infallible. 



i 4 o THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

These characteristics which pertain to the knowing act do, we 
believe, justify us in terming it an intuition, and since the 
knowing act is alone in possessing all these properties we shall 
use the term exclusively to signify knowing in this sense. For 
the sake of precision and consistency, therefore, we shall 
reject certain other usages of the term. For instance, we shall 
not call the hypotheses of the brilliant scientist 'intuitions'. 
He only intuits, in our sense, when he knows with certainty. 
Nor shall we talk of a woman's 'intuition', when we merely 
mean a form of shrewd guesswork. Nor again shall we use it 
in speaking of animal knowledge, if such knowledge be held 
to differ in kind from human knowledge. 1 Nor, finally, shall 
we continue to talk of 'sensuous intuition', if by this be meant 
the 'receiving' into the mind of a 'given' manifold, the affection 
of the mind in sensation. We shall reject all these usages f 
the term and confine it strictly to the act of knowing the real. 
The use of the phrase 'sensuous intuition', indeed, deserves 
more than a passing notice; for it leads to much confusion. 
By it is meant the seeing of the colour, the hearing of the sound, 
and so on. Now if we term these 'intuitions' we already suggest 
that they are instances of knowing. For to call something an 
'intuition' is to give it a cognitive character. It is impossible 
to rid the word of that suggestion. Accordingly, when the naive 
person refers to the seeing of the colour as a 'sensuous intuition' 
the phrase exactly expresses his meaning, since just seeing a 
colour is for him a knowing of the real. The critical person, 
however, cannot but be confused. He has realized that seeing a 
colour is not in itself an instance of knowing the real, as the 
naive person would claim. Yet if it is an 'intuition' it must, he 
also realizes, be a knowing of some kind. Hence his difficulty. 
As a consequence, he is frequently led to talk of vague knowing, 
or of half-knowledge, or of something which is just-not know- 
ledge; and the result is confused thinking. In other words, by 

1 In these pages we have not thought it necessary to consider at 
length the alleged * instinctive knowledge* of the lower animals, 
which, so some would urge, differs in kind from human knowledge. 
Our concern throughout is with the latter. 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 141 

terming the seeing of a colour and the hearing of a sound a 
'sensuous intuition* we are, to a certain degree, prejudicing 
the case from the outset. The very terms we use imply (whether 
we wish it or not) that seeing a colour is itself a knowing, and 
if we wish to avoid the implication we must avoid the use of the 
term in this connection, even though we feel that the word 
'intuition' does express some of the qualities which can be 
attributed to seeing a colour for instance, its directness. Fur- 
thermore, the use of the term makes a sound analysis of sensory 
experience well-nigh impossible. For its adoption is almost sure 
to result in an ignoring of the true knowing act present in the 
sensory experience. The full attention is bestowed upon the 
mere seeing of the colour, and by terming the latter an intui- 
tion' we suggest to ourselves and to everybody else that we are 
continuing to recognize the cognitive character of the sensory 
experience, although, as a matter of fact, we are completely 
ignoring it. The result is that we deceive ourselves, for, becom- 
ing critical and realizing that such a sensory experience (think- 
ing pf it as merely seeing the colour) provides no direct know- 
ledge of the real, we still think that in some vague fashion the 
seeing of the colour is a knowing. But if some other term had 
been used for the mere seeing of the colour, it would then be 
clear that the experience (if it is merely seeing a colour) is not 
cognitive at all. It would be clear that some essential element 
had been completely ignored. Our use of the phrase 'sensuous 
intuition', however, hides this all-important truth from us. 
Knowing becomes in part a 'reception' of a 'given', and in 
part a doing of something with this 'given', a constructing, a 
forming, an ordering of an objective world which exists as a 
vague shadowy structure of our own creation. And this con- 
fusing consequence, together with the resultant scepticism, is, 
we feel, the outcome of a false analysis of the sensory experience, 
whose falsity, we suggest, tends to be hidden from us by the 
use of the phrase 'sensuous intuition'. For this reason, there- 
fore, we consider the term 'sensuous intuition' an exceedingly 
dangerous one. 
We confine the term intuition, then, to the knowing act. In 



i 4 2 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

our opinion the term can be applied with justification to it 
alone. The reader, however, may well hesitate on one point 
before accepting our view. He may agree that knowing as such 
is something direct, immediate, and sui generis. He may also 
agree that it is not a process. In so far he would be prepared 
to term it intuitive in character. But an intuition, he feels, 
ought to be infallible. 1 Now nothing is more obvious than that 
human knowledge is fallible. How, then, can he and how can 
we call human knowledge 'intuitive'? The reader will have 
here touched upon a vexed question. But though the question 
he asks is not easily answered, we have no right to shirk it. 
For the sake of clearness we shall first put forward in one 
sentence the answer we suggest, after which we shall give reasons 
for holding it. The knowing act itself, we suggest, whenever it 
does occur, operates infallibly; but the concrete human cogni- 
tive experience taken as a whole is fallible. 

We have assumed throughout this essay that human knowing 
is a fact. We admit that we have given no definite proof of 
this, and, more, that no completely satisfactory proof of it js 
or ever will be possible. Against a thorough-going agnosticism 
we cannot bring a single argument. If the fact of knowing be 
granted, however, then it means that when a man is convinced 
that he knows he does, at least sometimes, know. Now if it were 
possible to show that his failures are due not to the functioning 
of that which we have called the knowing act but to something 
else in the whole experience of which the knowing act is part 
only, it would then be clear that the conviction which the 
knowing act inspires is completely trustworthy. What we are 
saying is that a man may be convinced, that is, satisfied in his 
mind and yet err this certainly cannot be denied; but that 
there is also a deeper conviction which cannot mislead. To say 
that this latter ever does mislead is to adopt agnosticism straight- 
way. For, if it fails us once, we cannot trust it on any other 

1 Most thinkers would agree that the term 'intuition' should be 
used to signify a knowledge which is infallible, and this is the view 
we adopt in these pages. To deprive it of this meaning would be, in 
our opinion, to emasculate it considerably. 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 143 

occasion. Our present task, therefore, is to show, in so far as we 
can, that the act of knowing itself is never erroneous, that error 
always enters in some other way. 1 

One type of error, frequently experienced, is obviously not 
due to any fallibility in the knowing act. We mean the type 
found in learning by testimony. The testimony may be of two 
kinds, firstly, that of other persons, or, secondly, that of our 
own memories. In the former case, error can easily enter. If I 
accept as true something which I have not seen to be true for 
myself, I may find later that I have fallen into error. Where 
we have to rely upon hearsay 'knowledge' we cannot rid ourselves 
completely of this possibility. The most reliable source of 
information sometimes fails us. Nevertheless, reliance on 
others in this sense is a necessity. For practical purposes we 
are frequently compelled to take another's word on a particular 
point. Especially does this hold true of ages and civilizations in 
which learning is advanced and in which specialization cannot 
be avoided, for then, because of our inevitable inexpertness in 
certain realms, we have to learn many items of knowledge not 
by finding out for ourselves, that is to say, speaking strictly, 
by knowing them ourselves, but by accepting the information 
given by another with regard to them. Now in such a case the 
important point is that our error, were we thus to accept what 
is not true, cannot possibly be due to the functioning of the 
kino wing act and does not make the latter fallacious, for merely 
to accept something as true on the \vord and authority of another 
is not to see its truth for oneself. Again, one's memory may 
fail. I may learn by rote at some time or other an item of 
knowledge originally gained either by directly apprehending it 
myself or by taking it as true on the authority of another. But 
later in recalling what I knew I may falsify it, usually because I 
give insufficient attention to the work of recollection. Now the 
term memory is, we admit, ambiguous and the problem of 

1 It seems hardly necessary to add that we do not mean spoken 
conviction in the above paragraph, for we sometimes say that we are 
convinced when we are not, and, occasionally, the less convinced we 
are the more vehement our speech becomes. 



144 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

memory supremely difficult. We do not here propose to discuss 
its nature. But when we mean by remembering remembering 
by rote, as in the present case, then remembering something 
obviously is not the same as knowing it. 1 And since this is so, a 
defect in the work of memorizing, as in the above instance, 
cannot rightly be attributed to the act of knowing. What we 
learn by testimony, therefore, may be erroneous, but in such a 
case our taking it as true is no failure of the knowing act. 
Slightly different from these instances, but worth mentioning 
none the less, is that type of error w r hich arises from a defect in 
the media through which we communicate information to 
each other. For instance, on a walk, I may see a person in a 
field nearby and ask him the distance to the neighbouring town. 
He knows that it is ten miles away and shouts it back to me. 
But his voice is not clear, or the wind is high,*and I hear, 
" Seven' '. Surely the resultant error is not attributable to any 
defect in my power to know nor, for that matter, in his. We 
need not further analyse these instances of erring, for all we 
wish to prove is that the knowing act as such is infallible, and 
in these cases it cannot possibly be held responsible for the 
occurrence of error. 

But in the above experiences the knowing act is absent, 
though it may be presupposed, for instance, in the knowing 
of my informant, or, again, in my own knowing of what I now 
recall. My * knowledge' by hearsay and my bare remembering 
by rote, however, are not, as such, acts of knowing. Yet there 
are other cognitive experiences which involve intuitive acts 
of knowing, and which, none the less, are fallible. We must 
now consider these. Is their fallibility due to a fallible knowing 
act ? Since we have just been considering the case of memory, 
we may begin with the consideration of erroneous cognitive 
experiences involving memory. Here is one such case: I see 

1 The case of erring in remembering a past event by recalling it 
in imagination is more difficult. No doubt cognitive elements are 
definitely present here. We cannot consider this case fully, however, 
without at the same time essaying an exhaustive analysis of the 
memory experience. 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 145 

directly that certain premisses involve a conclusion. I take these 
premisses to be true and accordingly assert the truth of the 
conclusion. The information contained in the premisses, how- 
ever, is simply remembered by me; and it may be false. If I 
then use the falsely recalled information my conclusion will be 
erroneous. Many errors in calculation can be accounted for in 
this way. As an instance, we may take the simplest form of 
calculation, namely, arithmetic. No one in his senses would 
say that twice one are equal to eight. We immediately 'per- 
ceive' that twice one is two. But if we were given a more com- 
plex multiplication problem, running into many figures, we 
might, owing to the strain upon our attention and the conse- 
quent mental fatigue, slip into taking seven times seven as 
being equal to fifty-six instead of forty-nine. The error would 
be duo to the fact that we were simply recalling, without 
'perceiving' the truth for ourselves, as when I 'perceive' that 
twice one are two. 1 The defect lies not in the knowing act but 
in the memory. Very many errors in calculation (not only in 
aritlynetic, but also in other spheres) are of this type. They 
result from the fact that memory gives us false premisses. And 
frequently, in such a case, our conviction that the premisses 
imply the conclusion is so strong that we accept the conclusion 
as absolutely (and not only provisionally) true, and even feel 
convinced about this. If in such a case, however, the conclusion 
is'not true, our error can be attributed to a double defect of 
memory. For, firstly, we faultily recollect one (or two or many) 
of the premisses, and, secondly, we completely forget that 
the premisses are unverified. If we remembered the latter 
point, our conviction as to the truth of the conclusion would 
speedily vanish. Now in such an experience as the above the 
defect which produces the error does not lie in the knowing 
act, for, though our premisses are false, it still remains true 
that they do imply the conclusion. The defect lies in the 
memory. 

1 This fact is confirmed by our having frequently to 'run over the 
whole table* when in doubt. Clearly, we are simply seeking to recall 
something previously learnt by rote. 



I 4 6 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

But not all human error originates in a defect of memory. 
For, as we see it, the type of error which is most prevalent finds 
its source elsewhere. It originates in man's impulse to complete 
the incomplete an impulse which in itself is perfectly legiti- 
mate. Our curiosity is such that we cannot remain satisfied with 
part-knowledge. And in our haste to press forward towards 
omniscience we frequently mistake something which is not 
knowing for knowing. Hence, error becomes possible. Knowing 
a part, we 'take' a whole; but, frequently, the 'taking* is not a 
knowing, and if we think that it is we fall into error. 

In this way we frequently mistake the probable for the 
certain. So long as we are clear in our own minds about the 
probability of the probable and neither think of it as, nor claim 
it to be, certain no error is involved in its assertion. But the 
moment we assert, or even implicitly assume, in our haste for 
finality, that the probable is certain, then error has already 
entered. So much is obvious. (In much the same way, we 
also err if we assert that what is really improbable is probable 
or that something has a greater or less degree of probability 
than it really has.) But how do we come to make the mistake of 
supposing the probable to be certain? Now, knowing and 
opining, we hold, are two states of mind distinct from each 
other, and if sufficient care is taken it is always possible to 
distinguish between them. I may be in a state of knowing 
something with certainty, as when, for instance, I see that the 
premisses of a syllogism imply the conclusion; or again, I may 
be in quite a different state of mind, namely, opining, as when I 
believe that a conclusion gained inductively is probably true. 
The latter is simply a well-grounded opinion, though an opinion 
which may be grounded upon much certain knowledge gained 
previously. (The better grounded the opinion the more know- 
ledge is presupposed in it.) Now it is possible for a man to 
ignore the probability of the probable and to believe, for the 
time being, that it is certain. It would, no doubt, be an exag- 
geration to say that he forces himself to believe this. But he 
ignores that which would establish the mere probability of his 
belief, and so imagines that he knows. His state, however, is 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 147 

surely different from that of the man who does know and 
knows that he knows. The conviction of the latter is not his. 
He has just stumbled into a kind of conviction or into belief, 
as the result of ignoring certain evidence. And what we suggest 
is that his lapse is the consequence of a desire natural to man 
for certainty and finality in knowledge. He has opined that 
such and such a position is sound and has slipped into the. 
belief that his opining is knowing. But his opinion may be un- 
sound, as all opinions may. Though he thinks it to be knowing 
it is still fallible. Yet this fact, namely, the fallibility of his 
experience, cannot be used as an argument to prove that know- 
ing as such is fallible, for knowing as such is ex hypothesi some- 
thing different from his state. "But/* it may be objected, 
"ought we not to face the possibility that we are always in his 
state ? -May we not always be in the state of thinking or believ- 
ing that we know without really knowing on any single occa- 
sion ?" Here, the objector would be admitting the distinction 
between the two states, whether there actually exists an instance 
of real knowing or not, and this admission is sufficient for the 
above argument. For all we wish to maintain is that we cannot 
prove the knowing act to be fallacious by saying that sometimes 
we err even when we imagine we know. The latter state is not 
really an instance of knowing with certainty, but of imagining 
that we know with certainty a very different thing. As to the 
actual existence of certain knowledge, we assume throughout 
this essay that we do sometimes know with certainty, and are 
not always, when we claim to know, mistaking a well-grounded 
opinion for certain knowledge. We cannot see that any other 
answer to the objection is possible. If the objector persists in 
doubting the existence of any certain knowledge, nothing more 
can be said on that head. 

We occasionally then mistake an opining for a knowing, but 
the fallibility of what we thus take to be knowing is no argument 
for the existence of a like fallibility in knowing itself. That 
we can so mistake something else for a knowing, and that we 
do so in order to satisfy our desire for complete knowledge, 
is confirmed by the attitude of the naive sensationalist. His 



i 4 8 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

error is perhaps the deepest and most fundamental of all. He 
mistakes not opining, but sensing for knowing. To the real 
actually known by him in the sensory experience he applies 
the content gained in the mere seeing of the colour, hearing 
of the sound, and so on, which so we argue are not in them- 
selves instances of knowing at all. And so he senses a 'real* 
world, as he thinks, of things having colours, tastes, smells, 
and so on. An activity of the mind, namely, the seeing of the 
colour, is assumed to be a knowing, when actually it is nothing 
of the kind. The mind desirous of a fully-determined and well- 
qualified reality applies the content of sensation to the real, 
exactly as if seeing the colour were itself a knowing of the 
real. In just the same way and for the same ultimate reasons 
the man of science may occasionally dress up the general struc- 
ture of the real whose nature he has apprehended* in the garb 
of imagery and hypothetical conceptions, and fall into believing 
that the skeleton so clothed is the fully real, and so forget that 
his 'world' is partially true only. In all these instances the error 
lies in our tendency to take as knowing what is actually, not 
knowing, and the source of the error is our desire for completion 
and totality in the objective world. In no case can the error be 
said to result from a defect in the knowing act itself. In no case 
do we find that the direct apprehension of the real has itsel 
given, instead of truth, error. 

We have here considered the main types of error. No doubt, 
however, there are other types. To be truly exhaustive we 
should have to consider every possible instance of error. 
Failing this, it would be a good exercise, if we had the space 
to spare, to consider in detail each single instance of the 'logical' 
and 'material' fallacies set forth in works on formal logic. We 
venture the opinion that here again we should never meet with 
an instance of a cognitive experience, in which the error could 
be attributed directly to the knowing act. Its source would lie 
elsewhere, namely, in the whole mental preparation for the 
act of knowing. But to carry out even this reduced task would 
be to pass beyond the scope of the present essay, and we shall 
not attempt it. We have stated earlier, however, that while we 



INTUITIVE APPREHENSION 149 

admit the fallibility of the cognitive experience taken as a whole, 
we cannot admit the fallibility of the knowing act as such. 
And our (admittedly incomplete) consideration of the main 
types of error certainly substantiates this position. The reader, 
as we have suggested earlier, may feel a certain hesitation in 
conceding the intuitive character of the knowing act on account 
of the patent fallibility of our cognitive experiences. But if he t 
now agrees that what applies to the whole cognitive experience 
need not and does not, so far as we can see apply to the 
knowing act as such, then we shall have done something to 
remove his qualms, and he will be in a better position to accept 
our general thesis. What we urge is, firstly, that the whole 
cognitive experience is not merely knowing, in the strict sense, 
it is also a seeing or an opining, a conceiving, an ordering, a 
classifying, and so on; and, secondly, that error has its source 
not in the knowing act, as such, but in some other part of that 
whole experience. 

Hence it is quite possible to hold, so far as the present evi- 
dence goes, that the knowing act possesses, together with all the 
other qualities mentioned, this further quality of infallibility, 
and that it is rightly termed an 'intuition' even in this sense. 
The error in the whole cognitive experience can be traced, we 
believe, to sources other than the functioning of the knowing 
act. We have, of course, never tried to prove that the cognitive 
experience in man is infallible; such a project could only be 
undertaken by a person who very foolishly closes his eyes to 
some of the most obvious facts of our finite experience. We 
merely make the claim that the term 'intuitive' can be applied 
to the act of knowing itself (which is part only of the whole 
cognitive experience) and that it can be so applied even though 
we recognize that anything which is intuitive must be infallible 
and cannot of itself be the source of error. None the less, the 
whole cognitive experience is fallible, for it invariably, so far as 
we can see, includes within it a preparation of some kind for 
knowing, which preparation may be defective, as when our 
premisses are false in reasoning. We can find no instance of a 
cognitive experience which is simple, in the sense that the 



150 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

whole experience consists of knowing (or intuiting) and nothing 
else. Therefore, the infallibility of the knowing act cannot in 
any way be taken to imply a like infallibility in the whole 
cognitive experience. We may err; but the error does not 
originate in the knowing act. The latter is in the full sense of 
that term an * intuition*. 



CONCLUSION 

WE are now in a position to draw our conclusions. These are 
hypothetical in character; that is to say, we do not wish to 
claim that this essay has finally established their truth. We 
are content to put them forward almost in the nature of sugges- 
tions, and had best present them in the following form: The 
problems connected with epistemology are more likely to b*e 
solved, we think, if we accept as working hypotheses two posi- 
tions. The first, that knowing, as such, is one and the same 
throughout, whatever the form of the whole cognitive experi- 
ence; the second, that this knowing, identical in character 
throughout experience, is best described as an intuitive appre- 
hension of the real. We believe that the inquiry, now concluded, 
fully .justifies us in making these suggestions. 

"In emphasizing the first point, that knowing as such is 
identical in character throughout experience, we definitely 
deny the existence of so many types or kinds of knowing, each 
distinct from the other. The evidence when carefully con- 
sidered supports the denial. We do not believe, for instance, 
that sensing is one kind of knowing, and that discursive 
reasoning is another, whilst intuiting is still a third completely 
distinct type. The real differences that exist between these 
cognitive experiences do not lie in the knowing as such. They 
lie elsewhere. Thus, the affection of the mind in sensation 
however it be explained is, we believe, an occasion for the 
occurrence of knowledge. But this knowledge, we affirm, is an 
intuitive apprehension of the real and does not differ in kind 
and character from knowledge on any other occasion. Or again, 
we may consider discursive reasoning. By terming a cognitive 
experience 'mediate' we convey the suggestion that the knowing 
present could not occur without a prior process of some kind, 
which liberates the knowing faculty, and enables the mind to 
know. Together with this we may also mean that this knowledge 
which we term 'mediate* is of an implication, so that v we come 
to know indirectly something about the subject of the conclusion 
at which we arrive by knowing the implication directly. But the 



152 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

actual knowing in discursive reasoning again is direct and not 
at all different, so far as we can see, from knowing in the 
sensory experience or from any other instance of knowing 
wherever it occurs. 

But while we emphasize the identity of knowing as such 
throughout these cognitive experiences we think it necessary 
to recognize a difference in kind between the two experiences of 
knowing and opining. Opining is not knowing become vague. 
Knowing does not shade off into opining. The difference be- 
tween the two is, in our opinion, absolute. When I opine I am 
not certain; when I know I am certain. We have not sought 
in these pages to give any account of opining, since it w r ould not 
be strictly relevant to the matter in hand. Our concern has been 
with knowing and not with opining, however well grounded 
it be. Unfortunately, however, the human mind can, as we havje 
already pointed out, mistake an opining for a knowing. We 
can fall into believing that we know when we are only opining. 
And this makes our sole criterion in knowing, namely, our 'own 
conviction that we are now knowing, untrustworthy. None the 
less, no other criterion exists. 1 Our only method of procedure 
is to subject our convictions to every possible test, to free our 
minds from all prejudices, to be very careful that we have not 
mistaken what is not knowing for knowing. And if after every 
possible test is made we are still convinced, then we can rest 

1 It would be of no avail to say here that coherence or corre- 
spondence is a criterion. For what we mean when we make such an 
assertion is that when I learn, for instance, that some theory or 
other is inconsistent with itself, I know (and am convinced that I 
know) that it involves falsehood. But if I am asked how I know this, 
I can only answer that I am convinced of it. My ciiterion is my own 
conviction. I know that I know. And I make my appeal to another 
on the confident assumption that his mind also possesses power to 
know, and that he will be as convinced of the impossibility of the 
self-contradictory as I am of it. That is to say, my ultimate appeal is 
not to the fact that the self-contradictory is impossible, but to the 
fact that I am convinced, and that you too, I confidently assume, 
will be convinced, that the self-contradictory is impossible. It is this 
conviction which is the ultimate criterion, and it alone. 



CONCLUSION 153 

assured that we are knowing. It may, of course, be said that 
we can never feel sure that every test has been tried and that, 
therefore, an element of doubt will always remain. But it is our 
assumption throughout that knowing does occur. And we 
believe that there are experiences where doubt never enters, 
however careful we be. Instances are to be found in the mathe- 
matical sciences, but are in no way confined to that sphere. W 
know the so-called Laws of Thought with complete certainty ; 
but better still we frequently see that one thing implies another 
beyond the possibility of any doubt. Our suggestion in these 
pages is that the conviction which the knowing act brings in 
its train is wholly trustworthy; that the untrustworthy con- 
viction arises from a mistaking of an opining for a knowing. 
And though it is difficult in actual practice to distinguish be- 
tween the two, yet the untrustworthiness of the latter cannot 
be attributed to the former. Meanwhile our own experience 
leads us to assert though it be an assertion without proof 
that the former type of conviction does most certainly exist, 
that occasionally we do most certainly know in the strictest 
sense of that term. 1 

In the second place, it has been our purpose in this essay to 
describe knowing as accurately as possible. And the conclusion 
to which we have come is this one : that if we do wish to de- 
cribe knowing in terms other than it itself, that is to say, if 
we wish to say something more than merely that knowing is 
knowing, just as seeing blue is seeing blue, then the most 
appropriate description of knowing, in our opinion, is 'an 
intuitive apprehension of the real.' We have already shown why 
we use the word 'intuitive* in this connection and we need not 
repeat the argument. Also, we have considered the word 
'apprehension', and have decided that the analogy which it 
suggests is most suitable for expressing the character of this 
knowing act. Finally, we have assumed from the outset of this 
essay that the object of knowing, when it actually occurs, is 

1 We ought, perhaps, to add that where knowing does not occur, 
opining is extremely valuable. We made this plain in the third section 
of the second chapter. 



154 THE NATURE OF KNOWING 

the real, what is; and that it is ridiculous to suppose otherwise. 
Knowing, therefore, we suggest, is best described as 'an intuitive 
apprehension of the real/ 

As a final word we shall add that our use of the phrase 'a 
knowing acf in this essay is also, in our opinion, justified. 
The apprehension is an act. By which we mean to convey, 
firstly, that knowing as such is not a process. We believe that 
to think of knowing as a process is to misconceive its character. 
This misconception, we think, is the outcome of confusing a 
process of reasoning which may be a necessary preparation for 
knowing with the actual knowing itself. The whole cognitive 
experience in discursive reasoning, for instance, always involves 
a thought-process ; but we cannot see that the knowing itself is 
ever a process. It is a simple act. In the second place, we think 
the term 'act' justified because it conveys the further meaning 
that the knowing is an actualization of a capacity. We possess 
throughout the power to know, but, on occasion, in the right 
circumstances, this potentiality is actualized. In this sense, 
again, knowing is an act. Finally, in the third place, we have 
been trying to confine our attention, so far as was possible, to 
the subjective side of the knowing experience, and to the actual 
knowing rather than to the object, or to the whole subject- 
object relation. And the use of the word 'act' tends, we think, 
to keep this fact before the reader. The subject of our inquiry 
throughout has been that mental functioning which is knowing 
and which we now think best to describe as the intuitive 
apprehension of the real.