Skip to main content

Full text of "The nature of the physical world"

See other formats


Marine  Biological  Laboratory  Library 

Woods  Hole,  Massachusetts 


From  the   estate   of  Eric  G.    Ball    -    1979 


c 


J  *S 


THE   NATURE 
OF  THE 

PHYSICAL  WORLD 


THE    NATURE 

OF  THE 

PHYSICAL   WORLD 


by 
A.  S.  EDDINGTON 

M.A.,  LL.D.,  D.SC,  F.R.S. 

Plumian  Professor  of  Astronomy 

in  the 

University  of  Cambridge 


THE 

GIFFORD  LECTURES 

1927 


NEW    YORK  : 
THE    MACMILLAN     COMPANY 

CAMBRIDGE,     ENGLAND: 
AT    THE    UNIVERSITY    PRESS 

I929 

All  rights  reserved 


Copyright,  1928, 
By  THE  MACMILLAN  COMPANY. 


Set  up  and  electrotyped. 
Published  November,   1928. 
Reprinted  February,  1929. 
Twice.  March,   1929. 

Reprinted  April,  1929 


SET  UP  BY  BROWN  BROTHERS  LINOTYPERS 

PRINTED    IN    THE    UNITED    STATES    OF   AMERICA 

BY    THE    FERRIS    PRINTING    COMPANY 


PREFACE 

This  book  is  substantially  the  course  of  Gifford  Lectures 
which   I   delivered  in   the   University   of   Edinburgh   in 
January  to  March  1927.     It  treats  of  the  philosophical 
outcome  of  the  great  changes  of  scientific  thought  which 
have  recently  come  about.    The  theory  of  relativity  and 
the  quantum  theory  have  led  to  strange  new  conceptions 
of  the  physical  world;  the  progress  of  the  principles  of 
thermodynamics  has  wrought  more  gradual  but  no  less 
profound  change.     The  first  eleven  chapters  are  for  the 
most  part  occupied  with  the  new  physical  theories,  with 
the  reasons  which  have  led  to  their  adoption,  and  es- 
pecially with   the   conceptions   which    seem   to   underlie 
them.     The  aim  is  to  make  clear  the  scientific  view  of 
the  world  as  it  stands  at  the  present  day,  and,  where  it 
is  incomplete,  to  judge  the  direction  in  which  modern 
ideas  appear  to  be  tending.     In  the  last  four  chapters  I 
consider  the   position  which  this  scientific  view   should 
occupy  in  relation  to  the  wider  aspects  of  human   ex- 
perience, including  religion.     The  general  spirit  of  the 
inquiry  followed  in  the  lectures  is  stated  in  the  concluding 
paragraph  of  the  Introduction  (p.  xviii). 

I  hope  that  the  scientific  chapters  may  be  read  with 
interest  apart  from  the  later  applications  in  the  book; 
'but  they  are  not  written  quite  on  the  lines  that  would 
have  been  adopted  had  they  been  wholly  independent. 
It  would  not  serve  my  purpose  to  give  an  easy  intro- 
duction to  the  rudiments  of  the  relativity  and  quantum 
theories;  it  was  essential  to  reach  the  later  and  more 
recondite  developments  in  which  the  conceptions  of  great- 
est philosophical  significance  are  to  be  found.  Whilst 
much  of  the  book  should  prove  fairly  easy  reading,  argu- 


vi  PREFACE 

ments  of  considerable  difficulty  have  to  be  taken  in  their 
turn. 

My  principal  aim  has  been  to  show  that  these  scien- 
tific developments  provide  new  material  for  the  philoso- 
pher. I  have,  however,  gone  beyond  this  and  indicated 
how  I  myself  think  the  material  might  be  used.  I  realise 
that  the  philosophical  views  here  put  forward  can  only 
claim  attention  in  so  far  as  they  are  the  direct  outcome 
of  a  study  and  apprehension  of  modern  scientific  work. 
General  ideas  of  the  nature  of  things  which  I  may  have 
formed  apart  from  this  particular  stimulus  from  science 
are  of  little  moment  to  anyone  but  myself.  But  although 
the  two  sources  of  ideas  were  fairly  distinct  in  my  mind 
when  I  began  to  prepare  these  lectures  they  have  become 
inextricably  combined  in  the  effort  to  reach  a  coherent 
outlook  and  to  defend  it  from  probable  criticism.  For 
that  reason  I  would  like  to  recall  that  the  idealistic  tinge 
in  my  conception  of  the  physical  world  arose  out  of  math- 
ematical researches  on  the  relativity  theory.  In  so  far  as 
I  had  any  earlier  philosophical  views,  they  were  of  an 
entirely  different  complexion. 

From  the  beginning  I  have  been  doubtful  whether  it 
was  desirable  for  a  scientist  to  venture  so  far  into  extra- 
scientific  territory.  The  primary  justification  for  such 
an  expedition  is  that  it  may  afford  a  better  view  of  his 
own  scientific  domain.  In  the  oral  lectures  it  did  not 
seem  a  grave  indiscretion  to  speak  freely  of  the  various 
suggestions  I  had  to  offer.  But  whether  they  should  be 
recorded  permanently  and  given  a  more  finished  appear- 
ance has  been  difficult  to  decide.  I  have  much  to  fear 
from  the  expert  philosophical  critic,  but  I  am  filled  with 
even  more  apprehension  at  the  thought  of  readers  who 
may  look  to  see  whether  the  book  is  uon  the  side  of  the 
angels"  and  judge  its  trustworthiness  accordingly.     Dur- 


PREFACE  vii 

ing  the  year  which  has  elapsed  since  the  delivery  of  the 
lectures  I  have  made  many  efforts  to  shape  this  and  other 
parts  of  the  book  into  something  with  which  I  might  feel 
better  content.  I  release  it  now  with  more  diffidence  than 
I  have  felt  with  regard  to  former  books. 

The  conversational  style  of  the  lecture-room  is  gen- 
erally considered  rather  unsuitable  for  a  long  book,  but 
I  decided  not  to  modify  it.  A  scientific  writer,  in  for- 
going the  mathematical  formulae  which  are  his  natural 
and  clearest  medium  of  expression,  may  perhaps  claim 
some  concession  from  the  reader  in  return.  Many  parts 
of  the  subject  are  intrinsically  so  difficult  that  my  only 
hope  of  being  understood  is  to  explain  the  points  as  I 
would  were  I  face  to  face  with  an  inquirer. 

It  may  be  necessary  to  remind  the  American  reader 
that  our  nomenclature  for  large  numbers  differs  from 
his,  so  that  a  billion  here  means  a  million  million. 

A.  S.  E. 
August  192S 


INTRODUCTION 

I  have  settled  down  to  the  task  of  writing  these  lectures 
and  have  drawn  up  my  chairs  to  my  two  tables.  Two 
tables!  Yes;  there  are  duplicates  of  every  object  about 
me — two  tables,  two  chairs,  two  pens. 

This  is  not  a  very  profound  beginning  to  a  course 
which  ought  to  reach  transcendent  levels  of  scientific 
philosophy.  But  we  cannot  touch  bedrock  immediately; 
we  must  scratch  a  bit  at  the  surface  of  things  first.  And 
whenever  I  begin  to  scratch  the  first  thing  I  strike  is — 
my  two  tables. 

One  of  them  has  been  familiar  to  me  from  earliest 
years.  It  is  a  commonplace  object  of  that  environment 
which  I  call  the  world.  How  shall  I  describe  it?  It  has 
extension;  it  is  comparatively  permanent;  it  is  coloured; 
above  all  it  is  substantial.  By  substantial  I  do  not  merely 
mean  that  it  does  not  collapse  when  I  lean  upon  it ;  I  mean 
that  it  is  constituted  of  "substance"  and  by  that  word 
I  am  trying  to  convey  to  you  some  conception  of  its 
intrinsic  nature.  It  is  a  thing;  not  like  space,  which  is 
a  mere  negation;  nor  like  time,  which  is — Heaven 
knows  what !  But  that  will  not  help  you  to  my  meaning 
because  it  is  the  distinctive  characteristic  of  a  "thing" 
to  have  this  substantiality,  and  I  do  not  think  substan- 
tiality can  be  described  better  than  by  saying  that  it  is 
the  kind  of  nature  exemplified  by  an  ordinary  table.  And 
so  we  go  round  in  circles.^  After  all  if  you  are  a  plain 
commonsense  man,  not  too  much  worried  with  scien- 
tific scruples,  you  will  be  confident  that  you  understand 
the  nature  of  an  ordinary  table.  I  have  even  heard 
of  plain  men  who  had  the  idea  that  they  could  better 
understand  the  mystery  of  their  own  nature  if  scientists 

ix 


x  INTRODUCTION 

would  discover  a  way  of  explaining  it  in  terms  of  the 
easily  comprehensible  nature  of  a  table. 

Table  No.  2  is  my  scientific  table.  It  is  a  more  recent 
acquaintance  and  I  do  not  feel  so  familiar  with  it.  It 
does  not  belong  to  the  world  previously  mentioned — 
that  world  which  spontaneously  appears  around  me  when 
I  open  my  eyes,  though  how  much  of  it  is  objective  and 
how  much  subjective  I  do  not  here  consider.  It  is  part 
of  a  world  which  in  more  devious  ways  has  forced 
itself  on  my  attention.  My  scientific  table  is  mostly 
emptiness.  Sparsely  scattered  in  that  emptiness  are! 
numerous  electric  charges  rushing  about  with  great 
speed;  but  their  combined  bulk  amounts  to  less  than  a 
billionth  of  the  bulk  of  the  table  itself.  Notwithstanding 
its  strange  construction  it  turns  out  to  be  an  entirely 
efficient  table.  It  supports  my  writing  paper  as  satisfac- 
torily as  table  No.  1 ;  for  when  I  lay  the  paper  on  it  the 
little  electric  particles  with  their  headlong  speed  keep 
on  hitting  the  underside,  so  that  the  paper  is  maintained 
in  shuttlecock  fashion  at  a  nearly  steady  level.  If  I  lean 
upon  this  table  I  shall  not  go  through;  or,  to  be  strictly 
accurate,  the  chance  of  my  scientific  elbow  going  through 
my  scientific  table  is  so  excessively  small  that  it  can  be 
neglected  in  practical  life.  Reviewing  their  properties 
one  by  one,  there  seems  to  be  nothing  to  choose  between 
the  two  tables  for  ordinary  purposes;  but  when  ab- 
normal circumstances  befall,  then  my  scientific  table 
shows  to  advantage.  If  the  house  catches  fire  my  sci- 
entific table  will  dissolve  quite  naturally  into  scientific 
smoke,  whereas  my  familiar  table  undergoes  a  metamor- 
phosis of  its  substantial  nature  which  I  can  only  regard 
as  miraculous. 

There  is  nothing  substantial  about  my  second  table. 
It  is  nearly  all  empty  space — space  pervaded,  it  is  true, 


INTRODUCTION  xi 

by  fields  of  force,  but  these  are  assigned  to  the  category 
of  "influences",  not  of  "things".  Even  in  the  minute 
part  which  is  not  empty  we  must  not  transfer  the  old 
notion  of  substance.  In  dissecting  matter  into  electric 
charges  we  have  travelled  far  from  that  picture  of  it 
which  first  gave  rise  to  the  conception  of  substance,  and 
the  meaning  of  that  conception — if  it  ever  had  any — 
has  been  lost  by  the  way.  The  whole  trend  of  modern 
scientific  views  is  to  break  down  the  separate  categories 
of  "things",  "influences",  "forms",  etc.,  and  to  substi- 
tute a  common  background  of  all  experience.  Whether 
we  are  studying  a  material  object,  a  magnetic  field,  a 
geometrical  figure,  or  a  duration  of  time,  our  scientific 
information  is  summed  up  in  measures ;  neither  the  appa- 
ratus of  measurement  nor  the  mode  of  using  it  suggests 
that  there  is  anything  essentially  different  in  these  prob- 
lems. The  measures  themselves  afford  no  ground  for 
a  classification  by  categories.  We  feel  it  necessary  to 
concede  some  background  to  the  measures — an  external 
world;  but  the  attributes  of  this  world,  except  in  so  far 
as  they  'are  reflected  in  the  measures,  are  outside  scien- 
tific scrutiny.  Science  has  at  last  revolted  against 
attaching  the  exact  knowledge  contained  in  these  meas- 
urements to  a  traditional  picture-gallery  of  conceptions 
which  convey  no  authentic  information  of  the  back- 
ground and  obtrude  irrelevancies  into  the  scheme  of 
knowledge. 

I  will  not  here  stress  .further  the  non-substantiality 
of  electrons,  since  it  is  scarcely  necessary  to  the  present 
line  of  thought.  Conceive  them  as  substantially  as  you 
will,  there  is  a  vast  difference  between  my  scientific  table 
with  its  substance  (if  any)  thinly  scattered  in  specks 
in  a  region  mosdy  empty  and  the  table  of  everyday 
conception  which  we  regard  as  the  type  of  solid  reality 


xii  INTRODUCTION 

— an  incarnate  protest  against  Berkleian  subjectivism. 
It  makes  all  the  difference  in  the  world  whether  the 
paper  before  me  is  poised  as  it  were  on  a  swarm  of  flies 
and  sustained  in  shuttlecock  fashion  by  a  series  of  tiny 
blows  from  the  swarm  underneath,  or  whether  it  is  sup- 
ported because  there  is  substance  below  it,  it  being  the 
intrinsic  nature  of  substance  to  occupy  space  to  the  exclu- 
sion of  other  substance;  all  the  difference  in  conception 
at  least,  but  no  difference  to  my  practical  task  of  writing 
on  the  paper. 

I  need  not  tell  you  that  modern  physics  has  by  deli- 
cate test  and  remorseless  logic  assured  me  that  my  sec- 
ond scientific  table  is  the  only  one  which  is  really  there — 
wherever  "there"  may  be.  On  the  other  hand  I  need 
not  tell  you  that  modern  physics  will  never  succeed  in 
exorcising  that  first  table — strange  compound  of  external 
nature,  mental  imagery  and  inherited  prejudice — which 
lies  visible  to  my  eyes  and  tangible  to  my  grasp.  We 
must  bid  good-bye  to  it  for  the  present  for  we  are  about 
to  turn  from  the  familiar  world  to  the  scientific  world 
revealed  by  physics.  This  is,  or  is  intended  to  be,  a 
wholly  external  world. 

"You  speak  paradoxically  of  two  worlds.  Are  they 
not  really  two  aspects  or  two  interpretations  of  one  and 
the  same  world?" 

Yes,  no  doubt  they  are  ultimately  to  be  identified 
after  some  fashion.  But  the  process  by  which  the  ex- 
ternal world  of  physics  is  transformed  into  a  world  of 
familiar  acquaintance  in  human  consciousness  is  outside 
the  scope  of  physics.  And  so  the  world  studied  accord- 
ing to  the  methods  of  physics  remains  detached  from 
the  world  familiar  to  consciousness,  until  after  the 
physicist  has  finished  his  labours  upon  it.  Provisionally, 
therefore,  we  regard  the  table  which  is  the  subject  of 


INTRODUCTION  xiii 

physical  research  as  altogether  separate  from  the  familiar 
table,  without  prejudging  the  question  of  their  ultimate 
identification.  It  is  true  that  the  whole  scientific 
inquiry  starts  from  the  familiar  world  and  in  the  end  it 
must  return  to  the  familiar  world;  but  the  part  of  the 
journey  over  which  the  physicist  has  charge  is  in  foreign 
territory. 

Until  recently  there  was  a  much  closer  linkage;  the 
physicist  used  to  borrow  the  raw  material  of  his  world 
from  the  familiar  world,  but  he  does  so  no  longer.  His 
raw  materials  are  aether,  electrons,  quanta,  potentials, 
Hamiltonian  functions,  etc.,  and  he  is  nowadays  scrupu- 
lously careful  to  guard  these  from  contamination  by  con- 
ceptions borrowed  from  the  other  world.  There  is  a 
familiar  table  parallel  to  the  scientific  table,  but  there  is 
no  familiar  electron,  quantum  or  potential  parallel  to  the 
scientific  electron,  quantum  or  potential.  We  do  not  even 
desire  to  manufacture  a  familiar  counterpart  to  these 
things  or,  as  we  should  commonly  say,  to  "explain"  the 
electron.  After  the  physicist  has  quite  finished  his  world- 
building  a  linkage  or  identification  is  allowed;  but  prema- 
ture attempts  at  linkage  have  been  found  to  be  entirely 
mischievous. 

Science  aims  at  constructing  a  world  which  shall  be 
symbolic  of  the  world  of  commonplace  experience.  It 
is  not  at  all  necessary  that  every  individual  symbol  that 
is  used  should  represent  something  in  common  experi- 
ence or  even  something  explicable  in  terms  of  com- 
mon experience.  The  man  in  the  street  is  always  mak- 
ing this  demand  for  concrete  explanation  of  the  things 
referred  to  in  science;  but  of  necessity  he  must  be 
disappointed.  It  is  like  our  experience  in  learning  to 
read.  That  which  is  written  in  a  book  is  symbolic  of  a 
story  in  real  life.     The  whole  intention  of  the  book  is 


xiv  INTRODUCTION 

that  ultimately  a  reader  will  identify  some  symbol,  say 
BREAD,  with  one  of  the  conceptions  of  familiar  life.  But 
it  is  mischievous  to  attempt  such  identifications  prema- 
turely, before  the  letters  are  strung  into  words  and 
the  words  into  sentences.  The  symbol  A  is  not  the 
counterpart  of  anything  in  familiar  life.  To  the  child 
the  letter  A  would  seem  horribly  abstract;  so  we  give 
him  a  familiar  conception  along  with  it.  "A  was  an 
Archer  who  shot  at  a  frog."  This  tides  over  his  imme- 
diate difficulty;  but  he  cannot  make  serious  progress  with 
word-building  so  long  as  Archers,  Butchers,  Captains, 
dance  round  the  letters.  The  letters  are  abstract,  and 
sooner  or  later  he  has  to  realise  it.  In  physics  we  have 
outgrown  archer  and  apple-pie  definitions  of  the  funda- 
mental symbols.  To  a  request  to  explain  what  an  electron 
really  is  supposed  to  be  we  can  only  answer,  "It  is  part 
of  the  A  B  c  of  physics". 

The  external  world  of  physics  has  thus  become  a  world 
of  shadows.  In  removing  our  illusions  we  have  removed 
the  substance,  for  indeed  we  have  seen  that  substance  is 
one  of  the  greatest  of  our  illusions.  Later  perhaps 
we  may  inquire  whether  in  our  zeal  to  cut  out  all  that  is 
unreal  we  may  not  have  used  the  knife  too  ruthlessly. 
Perhaps,  indeed,  reality  is  a  child  which  cannot  survive 
without  its  nurse  illusion.  But  if  so,  that  is  of  little  con- 
cern to  the  scientist,  who  has  good  and  sufficient  reasons 
for  pursuing  his  investigations  in  the  world  of  shadows 
and  is  content  to  leave  to  the  philosopher  the  determina- 
tion of  its  exact  status  in  regard  to  reality.  In  the  world 
of  physics  we  watch  a  shadowgraph  performance  of 
the  drama  of  familiar  life.  The  shadow  of  my 
elbow  rests  on  the  shadow  table  as  the  shadow  ink 
flows  over  the  shadow  paper.  It  is  all  symbolic,  and 
as   a   symbol  the  physicist  leaves  it.     Then  comes   the 


INTRODUCTION  xv 

alchemist  Mind  who  transmutes  the  symbols.  The 
sparsely  spread  nuclei  of  electric  force  become  a  tangible 
solid;  their  restless  agitation  becomes  the  warmth  of 
summer;  the  octave  of  aethereal  vibrations  becomes  a 
gorgeous  rainbow.  Nor  does  the  alchemy  stop  here.  In 
the  transmuted  world  new  significances  arise  which  are 
scarcely  to  be  traced  in  the  world  of  symbols;  so  that 
it  becomes  a  world  of  beauty  and  purpose — and,  alas,  suf- 
fering and  evil. 

The  frank  realisation  that  physical  science  is  con- 
cerned with  a  world  of  shadows  is  one  of  the  most  sig- 
nificant of  recent  advances.  I  do  not  mean  that  physicists 
are  to  any  extent  preoccupied  with  the  philosophical  impli- 
cations of  this.  From  their  point  of  view  it  is  not  so  much 
a  withdrawal  of  untenable  claims  as  an  assertion  of  free- 
dom for  autonomous  development.  At  the  moment  I  am 
not  insisting  on  the  shadowy  and  symbolic  character  of 
the  world  of  physics  because  of  its  bearing  on  philosophy, 
but  because  the  aloofness  from  familiar  conceptions  will 
be  apparent  in  the  scientific  theories  I  have  to  describe. 
If  you  are  not  prepared  for  this  aloofness  you  are 
likely  to  be  out  of  sympathy  with  modern  scientific 
theories,  and  may  even  think  them  ridiculous — as,  I 
daresay,  many  people  do. 

It  is  difficult  to  school  ourselves  to  treat  the  physical 
world  as  purely  symbolic.  We  are  always  relapsing  and 
mixing  with  the  symbols  incongruous  conceptions  taken 
from  the  world  of  consciousness.  Untaught  by  long 
experience  we  stretch  a  hand  to  grasp  the  shadow, 
instead  of  accepting  its  shadowy  nature.  Indeed,  unless 
we  confine  ourselves  altogether  to  mathematical  sym- 
bolism it  is  hard  to  avoid  dressing  our  symbols  in  deceit- 
ful clothing.  When  I  think  of  an  electron  there 
rises  to  my  mind  a  hardx  red,  tiny  ball;  the  proton  simi- 


xvi  INTRODUCTION 

larly  is  neutral  grey.  Of  course  the  colour  is  absurd — 
perhaps  not  more  absurd  than  the  rest  of  the  conception — 
but  I  am  incorrigible.  I  can  well  understand  that  the 
younger  minds  are  finding  these  pictures  too  concrete 
and  are  striving  to  construct  the  world  out  of  Hamil- 
tonian  functions  and  symbols  so  far  removed  from 
human  preconception  that  they  do  not  even  obey 
the  laws  of  orthodox  arithmetic.  For  myself  I  find  some 
difficulty  in  rising  to  that  plane  of  thought;  but  I  am 
convinced  that  it  has  got  to  come. 

In  these  lectures  I  propose  to  discuss  some  of  the 
results  of  modern  study  of  the  physical  world  which 
give  most  food  for  philosophic  thought.  This  will  include 
new  conceptions  in  science  and  also  new  knowledge.  In 
both  respects  we  are  led  to  think  of  the  material  uni- 
verse in  a  way  very  different  from  that  prevailing  at  the 
end  of  the  last  century.  I  shall  not  leave  out  of 
sight  the  ulterior  object  which  must  be  in  the  mind  of 
a  Gifford  Lecturer,  the  problem  of  relating  these 
purely  physical  discoveries  to  the  wider  aspects  and 
interests  of  our  human  nature.  These  relations  can- 
not but  have  undergone  change,  since  our  whole  concep- 
tion of  the  physical  world  has  radically  changed.  I  am 
convinced  that  a  just  appreciation  of  the  physical 
world  as  it  is  understood  to-day  carries  with  it  a  feeling 
of  open-mindedness  towards  a  wider  significance  tran- 
scending scientific  measurement,  which  might  have 
seemed  illogical  a  generation  ago;  and  in  the  later 
lectures  I  shall  try  to  focus  that  feeling  and  make 
inexpert  efforts  to  find  where  it  leads.  But  I  should 
be  untrue  to  science  if  I  did  not  insist  that  its  study  is 
an  end  in  itself.  The  path  of  science  must  be  pursued 
for  its  own  sake,  irrespective  of  the  views  it  may  afford 
of  a  wider  landscape;  in  this  spirit  we  must  follow  the 


INTRODUCTION  xvii 

path  whether  it  leads  to  the  hill  of  vision  or  the  tunnel 
of  obscurity.  Therefore  till  the  last  stage  of  the  course 
is  reached  you  must  be  content  to  follow  with  me  the 
beaten  track  of  science,  nor  scold  me  too  severely  for 
loitering  among  its  wayside  flowers.  That  is  to  be  the 
understanding  between  us.    Shall  we  set  forth? 


CONTENTS 

Preface  vii 

Introduction  xi 

Chapter  I.  The  Downfall  of  Classical  Physics  I 

II.  Relativity  20 

III.  Time  36 

IV.  The  Running-Down  of  the  Universe  63 
V.  "Becoming"  87 

VI.  Gravitation — the  Law  111 

VII.  Gravitation — the  Explanation  138 

VIII.  Man's  Place  in  the  Universe  163 

IX.  The  Quantum  Theory  179 

X.  The  New  Quantum  Theory  200 

XI.  World  Building  230 

XII.  Pointer  Readings  247 

XIII.  Reality                .  273 

XIV.  Causation  293 
XV.  Science  and  Mysticism  316 

Conclusion  343 

Index  355 


THE   NATURE 
OF  THE 

PHYSICAL   WORLD 


Chapter  I 

THE  DOWNFALL  OF  CLASSICAL  PHYSICS 

The  Structure  of  the  Atom.  Between  1905  and  1908  Ein- 
stein and  Minkowski  introduced  fundamental  changes  in 
our  ideas  of  time  and  space.  In  191 1  Rutherford  intro- 
duced the  greatest  change  in  our  idea  of  matter  since  the 
time  of  Democritus.  The  reception  of  these  two  changes 
was  curiously  different.  The  new  ideas  of  space  and  time 
were  regarded  on  all  sides  as  revolutionary;  they  were 
received  with  the  greatest  enthusiasm  by  some  and 
the  keenest  opposition  by  others.  The  new  idea  of  mat- 
ter underwent  the  ordinary  experience  of  scientific  dis- 
covery; it  gradually  proved  its  worth,  and  when  the 
evidence  became  overwhelmingly  convincing  it  quietly 
supplanted  previous  theories.  No  great  shock  was  felt. 
And  yet  when  I  hear  to-day  protests  against  the  Bolshev- 
ism of  modern  science  and  regrets  for  the  old-established 
order,  I  am  inclined  to  think  that  Rutherford,  not  Ein- 
stein, is  the  real  villain  of  the  piece.  When  we  compare 
the  universe  as  it  is  now  supposed  to  be  with  the  universe 
as  we  had  ordinarily  preconceived  it,  the  most  arresting 
change  is  not  the  rearrangement  of  space  and  time  by 
Einstein  but  the  dissolution  of  all  that  we  regard  as  most 
solid  into  tiny  specks  floating  in  void.  That  gives  an 
abrupt  jar  to  those  who  think  that  things  are  more  or 
less  what  they  seem.  The  revelation  by  modern  physics 
of  the  void  within  the  atom  is  more  disturbing  than 
the  revelation  by  astronomy  of  the  immense  void  of 
interstellar  space. 

The  atom  is  as  porous  as  the  solar  system.     If  we 
eliminated  all  the  unfilled  space  in  a  man's  body  and 


2  DOWNFALL  OF  CLASSICAL  PHYSICS 

collected  his  protons  and  electrons  into  one  mass,  the 
man  would  be  reduced  to  a  speck  just  visible  with  a 
magnifying  glass. 

This  porosity  of  matter  was  not  foreshadowed  in  the 
atomic  theory.  Certainly  it  was  known  that  in  a  gas 
like  air  the  atoms  are  far  separated,  leaving  a  great  deal 
of  empty  space;  but  it  was  only  to  be  expected  that  mate- 
rial with  the  characteristics  of  air  should  have  rela- 
tively little  substance  in  it,  and  "airy  nothing"  is  a  com- 
mon phrase  for  the  insubstantial.  In  solids  the  atoms 
are  packed  tightly  in  contact,  so  that  the  old  atomic 
theory  agreed  with  our  preconceptions  in  regard- 
ing solid  bodies  as  mainly  substantial  without  much 
interstice. 

The  electrical  theory  of  matter  which  arose  towards 
the  end  of  the  nineteenth  century  did  not  at  first  alter 
this  view.  It  was  known  that  the  negative  electricity 
was  concentrated  into  unit  charges  of  very  small  bulk; 
but  the  other  constituent  of  matter,  the  positive  elec- 
tricity, was  pictured  as  a  sphere  of  jelly  of  the  same 
dimensions  as  the  atom  and  having  the  tiny  negative 
charges  embedded  in  it.  Thus  the  space  inside  a  solid 
was  still  for  the  most  part  well  filled. 

But  in  191 1  Rutherford  showed  that  the  positive 
electricity  was  also  concentrated  into  tiny  specks.  His 
scattering  experiments  proved  that  the  atom  was  able  to 
exert  large  electrical  forces  which  would  be  impossible 
unless  the  positive  charge  acted  as  a  highly  concentrated 
source  of  attraction;  it  must  be  contained  in  a  nucleus 
minute  in  comparison  with  the  dimensions  of  the  atom. 
Thus  for  the  first  time  the  main  volume  of  the  atom  was 
entirely  evacuated,  and  a  "solar  system"  type  of  atom 
was  substituted  for  a  substantial  "billiard-ball".  Two 
years  later  Niels  Bohr  developed  his  famous  theory  on 


THE  STRUCTURE  OF  THE  ATOM  3 

the  basis  of  the  Rutherford  atom,  and  since  then  rapid 
progress  has  been  made.  Whatever  further  changes  of 
view  are  in  prospect,  a  reversion  to  the  old  substantial 
atoms  is  unthinkable. 

The  accepted  conclusion  at  the  present  day  is  that  all 
varieties  of  matter  are  ultimately  composed  of  two  ele- 
mentary constituents — protons  and  electrons.  Electrically 
these  are  the  exact  opposites  of  one  another,  the  proton 
being  a  charge  of  positive  electricity  and  the  electron 
a  charge  of  negative  electricity.  But  in  other  respects 
their  properties  are  very  different.  The  proton  has  1840 
times  the  mass  of  the  electron,  so  that  nearly  all  the 
mass  of  matter  is  due  to  its  constituent  protons. 
The  proton  is  not  found  unadulterated  except  in  hydro- 
gen, which  seems  to  be  the  most  primitive  form  of  mat- 
ter, its  atom  consisting  of  one  proton  and  one  electron. 
In  other  atoms  a  number  of  protons  and  a  lesser 
number  of  electrons  are  cemented  together  to  form 
a  nucleus;  the  electrons  required  to  make  up  the  bal- 
ance are  scattered  like  remote  satellites  of  the  nucleus, 
and  can  even  escape  from  the  atom  and  wander  freely 
through  the  material.  The  diameter  of  an  electron  is 
about  1/50,000  of  the  diameter  of  an  atom;  that  of  the 
nucleus  is  not  very  much  larger;  an  isolated  proton  is 
supposed  to  be  much  smaller  still. 

Thirty  years  ago  there  was  much  debate  over  the  ques- 
tion of  aether-drag — whether  the  earth  moving  round 
the  sun  drags  the  aether  with  it.  At  that  time  the  solidity 
of  the  atom  was  unquestioned,  and  it  was  difficult 
to  believe  that  matter  could  push  its  way  through  the 
aether  without  disturbing  it.  It  was  surprising  and  per- 
plexing to  find  as  the  result  of  experiments  that  no 
convection  of  the  aether  occurred.  But  we  now  realise 
that  the  aether  can  slip  through  the  atoms  as  easily  as 


4  DOWNFALL  OF  CLASSICAL  PHYSICS 

through  the  solar  system,  and  our  expectation  is  all  the 
other  way. 

We  shall  return  to  the  "solar  system"  atom  in  later 
chapters.  For  the  present  the  two  things  which  concern 
us  are  (i)  its  extreme  emptiness,  and  (2)  the  fact  that  it 
is  made  up  of  electrical  charges. 

Rutherford's  nuclear  theory  of  the  atom  is  not  usually 
counted  as  one  of  the  scientific  revolutions  of  the  present 
century.  It  was  a  far-reaching  discovery,  but  a  discovery 
falling  within  the  classical  scheme  of  physics.  The  nature 
and  significance  of  the  discovery  could  be  stated  in  plain 
terms,  i.e.  in  terms  of  conceptions  already  current  in 
science.  The  epithet  "revolutionary"  is  usually  reserved 
for  two  great  modern  developments — the  Relativity 
Theory  and  the  Quantum  Theory.  These  are  not 
merely  new  discoveries  as  to  the  content  of  the  world; 
they  involve  changes  in  our  mode  of  thought  about  the 
world.  They  cannot  be  stated  immediately  in  plain 
terms  because  we  have  first  to  grasp  new  conceptions 
undreamt  of  in  the  classical  scheme  of  physics. 

I  am  not  sure  that  the  phrase  "classical  physics"  has 
ever  been  closely  defined.  But  the  general  idea  is  that 
the  scheme  of  natural  law  developed  by  Newton  in  the 
Principia  provided  a  pattern  which  all  subsequent  devel- 
opments might  be  expected  to  follow.  Within  the  four 
corners  of  the  scheme  great  changes  of  outlook  were 
possible;  the  wave-theory  of  light  supplanted  the  cor- 
puscular theory;  heat  was  changed  from  substance  (calo- 
ric) to  energy  of  motion;  electricity  from  continuous 
fluid  to  nuclei  of  strain  in  the  aether.  But  this  was  all 
allowed  for  in  the  elasticity  of  the  original  scheme. 
Waves,  kinetic  energy,  and  strain  already  had  their 
place  in  the  scheme;  and  the  application  of  the  same 
conceptions  to  account  for  a  wider  range  of  phenomena 


THE  FITZGERALD  CONTRACTION  5 

was  a  tribute  to  the  comprehensiveness  of  Newton's 
original  outlook. 

We  have  now  to  see  how  the  classical  scheme  broke 
down. 

The  FitzGerald  Contraction.  We  can  best  start  from 
the  following  fact.  Suppose  that  you  have  a  rod  moving 
at  very  high  speed.  Let  it  first  be  pointing  transverse 
to  its  line  of  motion.  Now  turn  it  through  a  right  angle 
so  that  it  is  along  the  line  of  motion.  The  rod  contracts. 
It  is  shorter  when  it  is  along  the  line  of  motion  than 
when  it  is  across  the  line  of  motion. 

This  contraction,  known  as  the  FitzGerald  contrac- 
tion, is  exceedingly  small  in  all  ordinary  circumstances. 
It  does  not  depend  at  all  on  the  material  of  the  rod  but 
only  on  the  speed.  For  example,  if  the  speed  is  19  miles 
a  second — the  speed  of  the  earth  round  the  sun — the 
contraction  of  length  is  1  part  in  200,000,000,  or  2^4 
inches  in  the  diameter  of  the  earth. 

This  is  demonstrated  by  a  number  of  experiments  of 
different  kinds  of  which  the  earliest  and  best  known  is 
the  Michelson-Morley  experiment  first  performed  in 
1887,  repeated  more  accurately  by  Morley  and  Miller 
in  1905,  and  again  by  several  observers  within  the  last 
year  or  two.  I  am  not  going  to  describe  these  experi- 
ments except  to  mention  that  the  convenient  way  of 
giving  your  rod  a  large  velocity  is  to  carry  it  on  the 
earth  which  moves  at  high^  speed  round  the  sun.  Nor 
shall  I  discuss  here  how  complete  is  the  proof  afforded 
by  these  experiments.  It  is  much  more  important  that 
you  should  realise  that  the  contraction  is  just  what  would 
be  expected  from  our  current  knowledge  of  a  material 
rod. 

You  are  surprised  that  the  dimensions  of  a  moving, 


6  DOWNFALL  OF  CLASSICAL  PHYSICS 

rod  can  be  altered  merely  by  pointing  it  different  ways. 
You  expect  them  to  remain  unchanged.  But  which  rod 
are  you  thinking  of?  (You  remember  my  two  tables.) 
If  you  are  thinking  of  continuous  substance,  extending  in 
space  because  it  is  the  nature  of  substance  to  occupy 
space,  then  there  seems  to  be  no  valid  cause  for  a  change 
of  dimensions.  But  the  scientific  rod  is  a  swarm  of 
electrical  particles  rushing  about  and  widely  separated 
from  one  another.  The  marvel  is  that  such  a  swarm 
should  tend  to  preserve  any  definite  extension.  The 
particles,  however,  keep  a  certain  average  spacing  so 
that  the  whole  volume  remains  practically  steady;  they 
exert  electrical  forces  on  one  another,  and  the  volume 
which  they  fill  corresponds  to  a  balance  between  the 
forces  drawing  them  together  and  the  diverse  motions 
tending  to  spread  them  apart.  When  the  rod  is  set  in 
motion  these  electrical  forces  change.  Electricity  in 
motion  constitutes  an  electric  current.  But  electric 
currents  give  rise  to  forces  of  a  different  type  from  those 
due  to  electricity  at  rest,  viz.  magnetic  forces.  More- 
over these  forces  arising  from  the  motion  of  electric 
charges  will  naturally  be  of  different  intensity  in  the 
directions  along  and  across  the  line  of  motion. 

By  setting  in  motion  the  rod  with  all  the  little  electric 
charges  contained  in  it  we  introduce  new  magnetic  forces 
between  the  particles.  Clearly  the  original  balance  is 
upset,  and  the  average  spacing  between  the  particles 
must  alter  until  a  new  balance  is  found.  And  so  the 
extension  of  the  swarm  of  particles — the  length  of  the 
rod — alters. 

There  is  really  nothing  mysterious  about  the  Fitz- 
Gerald  contraction.  It  would  be  an  unnatural  property 
of  a  rod  pictured  in  the  old  way  as  continuous  substance 
occupying  space  in  virtue  of  its  substantiality;  but  it  is 


THE  FITZGERALD  CONTRACTION  7 

an  entirely  natural  property  of  a  swarm  of  particles  held 
in  delicate  balance  by  electromagnetic  forces,  and  occu- 
pying space  by  buffeting  away  anything  that  tries  to 
enter.  Or  you  may  look  at  it  this  way:  your  expecta- 
tion that  the  rod  will  keep  its  original  length  presup- 
poses, of  course,  that  it  receives  fair  treatment  and 
is  not  subjected  to  any  new  stresses.  But  a  rod  in  motion 
is  subjected  to  a  new  magnetic  stress,  arising  not  from 
unfair  outside  tampering  but  as  a  necessary  consequence 
of  its  own  electrical  constitution;  and  under  this  stress 
the  contraction  occurs.  Perhaps  you  will  think  that  if 
the  rod  were  rigid  enough  it  might  be  able  to  resist  the 
compressing  force.  That  is  not  so;  the  FitzGerald  con- 
traction is  the  same  for  a  rod  of  steel  and  for  a  rod  of 
india-rubber;  the  rigidity  and  the  compressing  stress  are 
bound  up  with  the  constitution  in  such  a  way  that  if 
one  is  large  so  also  is  the  other.  It  is  necessary  to  rid 
our  minds  of  the  idea  that  this  failure  to  keep  a  constant 
length  is  an  imperfection  of  the  rod;  it  is  only  imperfect 
as  compared  with  an  imaginary  "something"  which  has 
not  this  electrical  constitution — and  therefore  is  not 
material  at  all.  The  FitzGerald  contraction  is  not  an 
imperfection  but  a  fixed  and  characteristic  property  of 
matter,  like  inertia. 

We  have  here  drawn  a  qualitative  inference  from  the 
electrical  structure  of  matter;  we  must  leave  it  to  the 
mathematician  to  calculate  the  quantitative  effect.  The 
problem  was  worked  out  by  Lorentz  and  Larmor  about 
1900.  They  calculated  the  change  in  the  average  spacing 
of  the  particles  required  to  restore  the  balance  after  it 
had  been  upset  by  the  new  forces  due  to  the  change  of 
motion  of  the  charges.  This  calculation  was  found  to 
give  precisely  the  FitzGerald  contraction,  i.e.  the  amount 
already  inferred  from  the  experiments  above  mentioned. 


8  DOWNFALL  OF  CLASSICAL  PHYSICS 

Thus  we  have  two  legs  to  stand  on.  Some  will  prefer  to 
trust  the  results  because  they  seem  to  be  well  established 
by  experiment;  others  will  be  more  easily  persuaded  by 
the  knowledge  that  the  FitzGerald  contraction  is  a 
necessary  consequence  of  the  scheme  of  electromag- 
netic laws  universally  accepted  since  the  time  of  Max- 
well. Both  experiments  and  theories  sometimes  go 
wrong;  so  it  is  just  as  well  to  have  both  alternatives. 

Consequences  of  the  Contraction.  This  result  alone, 
although  it  may  not  quite  lead  you  to  the  theory  of  rela- 
tivity, ought  to  make  you  uneasy  about  classical  physics. 
The  physicist  when  he  wishes  to  measure  a  length — 
and  he  cannot  get  far  in  any  experiment  without  meas- 
uring a  length — takes  a  scale  and  turns  it  in  the  direc- 
tion needed.  It  never  occurred  to  him  that  in  spite 
of  all  precautions  the  scale  would  change  length  when 
he  did  this;  but  unless  the  earth  happens  to  be  at  rest 
a  change  must  occur.  The  constancy  of  a  measur- 
ing scale  is  the  rock  on  which  the  whole  structure  of 
physics  has  been  reared;  and  that  rock  has  crumbled 
away.  You  may  think  that  this  assumption  cannot  have 
betrayed  the  physicist  very  badly;  the  changes  of  length 
cannot  be  serious  or  they  would  have  been  noticed. 
Wait  and  see. 

Let  us  look  at  some  of  the  consequences  of  the  Fitz- 
Gerald contraction.  First  take  what  may  seem  to  be  a 
rather  fantastic  case.  Imagine  you  are  on  a  planet  mov- 
ing very  fast  indeed,  say  161,000  miles  a  second.  For 
this  speed  the  contraction  is  one-half.  Any  solid  con- 
tracts to  half  its  original  length  when  turned  from  across 
to  along  the  line  of  motion.  A  railway  journey  between 
two  towns  which  was  100  miles  at  noon  is  shortened  to 
50  miles  at  6  p.m.  when  the  planet  has  turned  through 


CONSEQUENCES  OF  THE  CONTRACTION        9 

a  right  angle.  The  inhabitants  copy  Alice  in  Wonder- 
land; they  pull  out  and  shut  up  like  a  telescope. 

I  do  not  know  of  a  planet  moving  at  161,000  miles 
a  second,  but  I  could  point  to  a  spiral  nebula  far  away 
in  space  which  is  moving  at  1000  miles  a  second.  This 
may  well  contain  a  planet  and  (speaking  unprofession- 
ally)  perhaps  I  shall  not  be  taking  too  much  licence  if 
I  place  intelligent  beings  on  it.  At  1000  miles  a  second 
the  contraction  is  not  large  enough  to  be  appreciable  in 
ordinary  affairs;  but  it  is  quite  large  enough  to  be  appre- 
ciable in  measurements  of  scientific  or  even  of  engi- 
neering accuracy.  One  of  the  most  fundamental  pro- 
cedures in  physics  is  to  measure  lengths  with  a  scale 
moved  about  in  any  way.  Imagine  the  consternation  of 
the  physicists  on  this  planet  when  they  learn  that  they 
have  made  a  mistake  in  supposing  that  their  scale  is  a 
constant  measure  of  length.  What  a  business  to  go  back 
over  all  the  experiments  ever  performed,  apply  the 
corrections  for  orientation  of  the  scale  at  the  time,  and 
then  consider  de  novo  the  inferences  and  system  of 
physical  laws  to  be  deduced  from  the  amended  data ! 
How  thankful  our  own  physicists  ought  to  be  that  they 
are  not  in  this  runaway  nebula  but  on  a  decently  slow- 
moving  planet  like  the  earth ! 

But  stay  a  moment.  Is  it  so  certain  that  we  are  on 
a  slow-moving  planet?  I  can  imagine  the  astronomers 
in  that  nebula  observing  far  away  in  space  an  insignifi- 
cant star  attended  by  an  insignificant  planet  called 
Earth.  They  observe  too  that  it  is  moving  with  the 
huge  velocity  of  1000  miles  a  second;  because  naturally 
if  we  see  them  receding  from  us  at  1000  miles  a  second 
they  will  see  us  receding  from  them  at  1000  miles  a 
second.  "A  thousand  miles  a  second!"  exclaim  the 
nebular    physicists,    "How    unfortunate    for    the    poor 


io  DOWNFALL  OF  CLASSICAL  PHYSICS 

physicists  on  the  Earth!  The  FitzGerald  contraction 
will  be  quite  appreciable,  and  all  their  measures  with 
scales  will  be  seriously  wrong.  What  a  weird  system  of 
laws  of  Nature  they  will  have  deduced,  if  they  have  over- 
looked this  correction !" 

There  is  no  means  of  deciding  which  is  right — to 
which  of  us  the  observed  relative  velocity  of  iooo 
miles  a  second  really  belongs.  Astronomically  the  gal- 
axy of  which  the  earth  is  a  member  does  not  seem  to 
be  more  important,  more  central,  than  the  nebula. 
The  presumption  that  it  is  we  who  are  the  more  nearly 
at  rest  has  no  serious  foundation;  it  is  mere  self- 
flattery. 

"But",  you  will  say,  "surely  if  these  appreciable 
changes  of  length  occurred  on  the  earth,  we  should 
detect  them  by  our  measurements."  That  brings  me  to 
the  interesting  point.  We  could  not  detect  them  by  any 
measurement;  they  may  occur  and  yet  pass  quite  un- 
noticed.    Let  me  try  to  show  how  this  happens. 

This  room,  we  will  say,  is  travelling  at  161,000  miles 
a  second  vertically  upwards.  That  is  my  statement,  and 
it  is  up  to  you  to  prove  it  wrong.  I  turn  my  arm  from 
horizontal  to  vertical  and  it  contracts  to  half  its  original 
length.  You  don't  believe  me?  Then  bring  a  yard- 
measure  and  measure  it.  First,  horizontally,  the  result 
is  30  inches;  now  vertically,  the  result  is  30  half-inches. 
You  must  allow  for  the  fact  that  an  inch-division  of  the 
scale  contracts  to  half  an  inch  when  the  yard-measure 
is  turned  vertically. 

"But  we  can  see  that  your  arm  does  not  become 
shorter;  can  we  not  trust  our  own  eyes?" 

Certainly  not,  unless  you  remember  that  when  you 
got  up  this  morning  your  retina  contracted  to  half  its 
original  width  in  the  vertical  direction;  consequently  it 


CONSEQUENCES  OF  THE  CONTRACTION       n 

is  now  exaggerating  vertical  distances  to  twice  the  scale 
of  horizontal  distances. 

"Very  well",  you  reply,  "I  will  not  get  up.  I  will  lie 
in  bed  and  watch  you  go  through  your  performance  in 
an  inclined  mirror.  Then  my  retina  will  be  all  right, 
but  I  know  I  shall  still  see  no  contraction." 

But  a  moving  mirror  does  not  give  an  undistorted 
image  of  what  is  happening.  The  angle  of  reflection  of 
light  is  altered  by  motion  of  a  mirror,  just  as  the  angle 
of  reflection  of  a  billiard-ball  would  be  altered  if  the 
cushion  were  moving.  If  you  will  work  out  by  the 
ordinary  laws  of  optics  the  effect  of  moving  a  mirror  at 
161,000  miles  a  second,  you  will  find  that  it  introduces 
a  distortion  which  just  conceals  the  contraction  of  my 
arm. 

And  so  on  for  every  proposed  test.  You  cannot 
disprove  my  assertion,  and,  of  course,  I  cannot  prove 
it;  I  might  equally  well  have  chosen  and  defended  any 
other  velocity.  At  first  this  seems  to  contradict  what 
I  told  you  earlier — that  the  contraction. had  been  proved 
and  measured  by  the  Michelson-Morley  and  other  experi- 
ments— but  there  is  really  no  contradiction.  They  were 
all  null  experiments,  just  as  your  experiment  of  watch- 
ing my  arm  in  an  inclined  mirror  was  a  null  experiment. 
Certain  optical  or  electrical  consequences  of  the  earth's 
motion  were  looked  for  of  the  same  type  as  the 
distortion  of  images  by  a  moving  mirror;  these  would 
have  been  observed  unless  a  contraction  occurred  of 
just  the  right  amount  to  compensate  them.  They 
were  not  observed;  therefore  the  compensating  contrac- 
tion had  occurred.  There  was  just  one  alternative;  the 
earth's  true  velocity  through  space  might  happen  to 
have  been  nil.  This  was  ruled  out  by  repeating  the 
experiment  six  months   later,   since   the   earth's   motion 


12  DOWNFALL  OF  CLASSICAL  PHYSICS 

could  not  be  nil  on  both  occasions.  Thus  the  contraction 
was  demonstrated  and  its  law  of  dependence  on  velocity 
verified.  But  the  actual  amount  of  contraction  on  either 
occasion  was  unknown,  since  the  earth's  true  velocity 
(as  distinct  from  its  orbital  velocity  with  respect  to  the 
sun)  was  unknown.  It  remains  unknown  because  the 
optical  and  electrical  effects  by  which  we  might  hope 
to  measure  it  are  always  compensated  by  the  contraction. 
I  have  said  that  the  constancy  of  a  measuring  scale  is 
the  rock  on  which  the  structure  of  physics  has  been 
reared.  The  structure  has  also  been  supported  by  sup- 
plementary props  because  optical  and  electrical  devices 
can  often  be  used  instead  of  material  scales  to  ascertain 
lengths  and  distances.  But  we  find  that  all  these  are 
united  in  a  conspiracy  not  to  give  one  another  away. 
The  rock  has  crumbled  and  simultaneously  all  the  other 
supports  have  collapsed. 

Frames  of  Space.  We  can  now  return  to  the  quarrel 
between  the  nebular  physicists  and  ourselves.  One  of  us 
has  a  large  velocity  and  his  scientific  measurements  are 
seriously  affected  by  the  contraction  of  his  scales.  Each 
has  hitherto  taken  it  for  granted  that  it  is  the  other 
fellow  who  is  making  the  mistake.  We  cannot  settle 
the  dispute  by  appeal  to  experiment  because  in  every 
experiment  the  mistake  introduces  two  errors  which  just 
compensate  one  another. 

It  is  a  curious  sort  of  mistake  which  always  carries 
with  it  its  own  compensation.  But  remember  that  the 
compensation  only  applies  to  phenomena  actually  ob- 
served or  capable  of  observation.  The  compensation 
does  not  apply  to  the  intermediate  part  of  our  deduc- 
tion— that  system  of  inference  from  observation  which 
forms  the  classical  physical  theory  of  the  universe. 


FRAMES  OF  SPACE  13 

Suppose  that  we  and  the  nebular  physicists  survey 
the  world,  that  is  to  say  we  allocate  the  surrounding 
objects  to  their  respective  positions  in  space.  One 
party,  say  the  nebular  physicists,  has  a  large  velocity; 
their  yard-measures  will  contract  and  become  less  than 
a  yard  when  they  measure  distances  in  a  certain  direc- 
tion; consequently  they  will  reckon  distances  in  that 
direction  too  great.  It  does  not  matter  whether  they 
use  a  yard-measure,  or  a  theodolite,  or  merely  judge 
distances  with  the  eye;  all  methods  of  measurement 
must  agree.  If  motion  caused  a  disagreement  of  any 
kind,  we  should  be  able  to  determine  the  motion  by 
observing  the  amount  of  disagreement;  but,  as  we  have 
already  seen,  both  theory  and  observation  indicate  that 
there  is  complete  compensation.  If  the  nebular  physi- 
cists try  to  construct  a  square  they  will  construct  an 
oblong.  No  test  can  ever  reveal  to  them  that  it  is  not  a 
square;  the  greatest  advance  they  can  make  is  to  recog- 
nise that  there  are  people  in  another  world  who  have  got 
it  into  their  heads  that  it  is  an  oblong,  and  they  may  be 
broadminded  enough  to  admit  that  this  point  of  view,  ab- 
surd as  it  seems,  is  really  as  defensible  as  their  own.  It 
is  clear  that  their  whole  conception  of  space  is  distorted 
as  compared  with  ours,  and  ours  is  distorted  as  com- 
pared with  theirs.  We  are  regarding  the  same  universe, 
but  we  have  arranged  it  in  different  spaces.  The  original 
quarrel  as  to  whether  they  or  we  are  moving  with  the 
speed  of  1000  miles  a  second  has  made  so  deep  a  cleavage 
between  us  that  we  cannot  even  use  the  same  space. 

Space  and  time  are  words  conveying  more  than  one 
meaning.  Space  is  an  empty  void;  or  it  is  such  and  such 
a  number  of  inches,  acres,  pints.  Time  is  an  ever-rolling 
stream;  or  it  is  something  signalled  to  us  by  wireless. 
The  physicist  has  no  use  for  vague  conceptions;  he  often 


i4  DOWNFALL  OF  CLASSICAL  PHYSICS 

has  them,  alas !  but  he  cannot  make  real  use  of  them. 
So  when  he  speaks  of  space  it  is  always  the  inches  or 
pints  that  he  should  have  in  mind.  It  is  from  this  point 
of  view  that  our  space  and  the  space  of  the  nebular 
physicists  are  different  spaces;  the  reckoning  of  inches 
and  pints  is  different.  To  avoid  possible  misunder- 
standing it  is  perhaps  better  to  say  that  we  have  different 
frames  of  space — different  frames  to  which  we  refer  the 
location  of  objects.  Do  not,  however,  think  of  a  frame 
of  space  as  something  consciously  artificial;  the  frame 
of  space  comes  into  our  minds  with  our  first  perception  of 
space.  Consider,  for  example,  the  more  extreme  case 
when  the  FitzGerald  contraction  is  one-half.  If  a  man 
takes  a  rectangle  2"Xi"  to  be  a  square  it  is  clear  that 
space  must  have  dawned  on  his  intelligence  in  a  way  very 
different  from  that  in  which  we  have  apprehended  it. 

The  frame  of  space  used  by  an  observer  depends  only 
on  his  motion.  Observers  on  different  planets  with  the 
same  velocity  (i.e.  having  zero  relative  velocity)  will 
agree  as  to  the  location  of  the  objects  of  the  universe; 
but  observers  on  planets  with  different  velocities  have 
different  frames  of  location.  You  may  ask,  How  can 
I  be  so  confident  as  to  the  way  in  which  these  imaginary 
beings  will  interpret  their  observations?  If  that  objec- 
tion is  pressed  I  shall  not  defend  myself;  but  those  who 
dislike  my  imaginary  beings  must  face  the  alternative 
of  following  the  argument  with  mathematical  symbols. 
Our  purpose  has  been  to  express  in  a  conveniently 
apprehensible  form  certain  results  which  follow  from 
terrestrial  experiments  and  calculations  as  to  the  effect 
of  motion  on  electrical,  optical  and  metrical  phenomena. 
So  much  careful  work  has  been  done  on  this  subject 
that  science  is  in  a  position  to  state  what  will  be  the 
consequence   of  making  measurements  with   instruments 


FRAMES  OF  SPACE  15 

travelling  at  high  speed — whether  instruments  of  a 
technical  kind  or,  for  example,  a  human  retina.  In  only 
one  respect  do  I  treat  my  nebular  observer  as  more  than 
a  piece  of  registering  apparatus;  I  assume  that  he  is 
subject  to  a  common  failing  of  human  nature,  viz.  he 
takes  it  for  granted  that  it  was  his  planet  that  God 
chiefly  had  in  mind  when  the  universe  was  created. 
Hence  he  is  (like  my  reader  perhaps?)  disinclined  to 
take  seriously  the  views  of  location  of  those  people  who 
are  so  misguided  as  to  move  at  1000  miles  a  second 
relatively  to  his  parish  pump. 

An  exceptionally  modest  observer  might  take  some 
other  planet  than  his  own  as  the  standard  of  rest.  Then 
he  would  have  to  correct  all  his  measurements  for  the 
FitzGerald  contraction  due  to  his  own  motion  with 
respect  to  the  standard,  and  the  corrected  measures 
would  give  the  space-frame  belonging  to  the  standard 
planet  as  the  original  measures  gave  the  space-frame  of 
his  own  planet.  For  him  the  dilemma  is  even  more 
pressing,  for  there  is  nothing  to  guide  him  as  to  the 
planet  to  be  selected  for  the  standard  of  rest.  Once 
he  gives  up  the  naive  assumption  that  his  own  frame  is 
the  one  and  only  right  frame  the  question  arises,  Which 
then  of  the  innumerable  other  frames  is  right?  There 
is  no  answer,  and  so  far  as  we  can  see  no  possibility  of 
an  answer.  Meanwhile  all  his  experimental  measure- 
ments are  waiting  unreduced,  because  the  corrections 
to  be  applied  to  them  depend  on  the  answer.  I  am 
afraid  our  modest  observer  will  get  rather  left  behind 
by  his  less  humble  colleagues. 

The  trouble  that  arises  is  not  that  we  have  found 
anything  necessarily  wrong  with  the  frame  of  location 
that  has  been  employed  in  our  system  of  physics;  it  has 
not  led  to  experimental  contradictions.     The  only  thing 


16  DOWNFALL  OF  CLASSICAL  PHYSICS 

known  to  be  "wrong"  with  it  is  that  it  is  not  unique. 
If  we  had  found  that  our  frame  was  unsatisfactory  and 
another  frame  was  preferable,  that  would  not  have 
caused  a  great  revolution  of  thought;  but  to  discover 
that  ours  is  one  of  many  frames,  all  of  which  are  equally 
satisfactory,  leads  to  a  change  of  interpretation  of  the 
significance  of  a  frame  of  location. 

"Commonsense"  Objections.  Before  going  further  I  must 
answer  the  critic  who  objects  in  the  name  of  common- 
sense.  Space — his  space — is  so  vivid  to  him.  "This 
object  is  obviously  here;  that  object  is  just  there.  I  know 
it;  and  I  am  not  going  to  be  shaken  by  any  amount  of  sci- 
entific obscurantism  about  contraction  of  measuring  rods." 
We  have  certain  preconceived  ideas  about  location 
in  space  which  have  come  down  to  us  from  ape-like 
ancestors.  They  are  deeply  rooted  in  our  mode  of 
thought,  so  that  it  is  very  difficult  to  criticise  them 
impartially  and  to  realise  the  very  insecure  foundation 
on  which  they  rest.  We  commonly  suppose  that  each 
of  the  objects  surrounding  us  has  a  definite  location  in 
space  and  that  we  are  aware  of  the  right  location.  The 
objects  in  my  study  are  actually  in  the  positions  where 
I  am  "aware"  that  they  are;  and  if  an  observer  (on 
another  star)  surveying  the  room  with  measuring  rods, 
etc.,  makes  out  a  different  arrangement  of  location,  he 
is  merely  spinning  a  scientific  paradox  which  does  not 
shake  the  real  facts  of  location  obvious  to  any  man 
of  commonsense.  This  attitude  rejects  with  contempt 
the  question,  How  am  I  aware  of  the  location?  If  the 
location  is  determined  by  scientific  measurements  with 
elaborate  precautions,  we  are  ready  enough  to  sug- 
gest all  sorts  of  ways  in  which  the  apparatus  might 
have  misbehaved;  but  if  the  knowledge  of  location  is 


a 


COMMONSENSE"  OBJECTIONS  17 


obtained  with  no  precautions,  if  it  just  comes  into  our 
heads  unsought,  then  it  is  obviously  true  and  to  doubt 
it  would  be  flying  in  the  face  of  commonsense !  We 
have  a  sort  of  impression  (although  we  do  not  like 
to  acknowledge  it)  that  the  mind  puts  out  a  feeler  into 
space  to  ascertain  directly  where  each  familiar  object  is. 
That  is  nonsense;  our  commonsense  knowledge  of  location 
is  not  obtained  that  way.  Strictly  it  is  sense  knowledge, 
not  commonsense  knowledge.  It  is  partly  obtained 
by  touch  and  locomotion;  such  and  such  an  object 
is  at  arm's  length  or  a  few  steps  away.  Is  there 
any  essential  difference  (other  than  its  crudity)  between 
this  method  and  scientific  measurements  with  a  scale? 
It  is  partly  obtained  by  vision — a  crude  version  of 
scientific  measurement  with  a  theodolite.  Our  common 
knowledge  of  where  things  are  is  not  a  miraculous 
revelation  of  unquestionable  authority;  it  is  inference 
from  observations  of  the  same  kind  as,  but  cruder  than, 
those  made  in  a  scientific  survey.  Within  its  own  limits 
of  accuracy  the  scheme  of  location  of  objects  that  I  am 
instinctively  "aware"  of  is  the  same  as  my  scientific 
scheme  of  location,  or  frame  of  space. 

When  we  use  a  carefully  made  telescope  lens  and  a 
sensitised  plate  instead  of  the  crystalline  lens  and  retina 
of  the  eye  we  increase  the  accuracy  but  do  not  alter  the 
character  of  our  survey  of  space.  It  is  by  this  increase 
of  refinement  that  we  have  become  "aware"  of  certain 
characteristics  of  space  which  were  not  known  to  our 
ape-like  ancestor  when  he  instituted  the  common  ideas 
that  have  come  down  to  us.  His  scheme  of  location 
works  consistently  so  long  as  there  is  no  important 
change  in  his  motion  (a  few  miles  a  second  makes  no 
appreciable  difference) ;  but  a  large  change  involves  a 
transition  to  a  different  system  of  location  which  is  like- 


18  DOWNFALL  OF  CLASSICAL  PHYSICS 

wise  self-consistent,  although  it  is  inconsistent  with  the 
original  one.  Having  any  number  of  these  systems  of 
location,  or  frames  of  space,  we  can  no  longer  pretend 
that  each  of  them  indicates  "just  where  things  are". 
Location  is  not  something  supernaturally  revealed  to  the 
mind;  it  is  a  kind  of  conventional  summary  of  those 
properties  or  relations  of  objects  which  condition  certain 
visual  and  tactual  sensations. 

Does  not  this  show  that  "right"  location  in  space 
cannot  be  nearly  so  important  and  fundamental  as  it  is 
made  out  to  be  in  the  Newtonian  scheme  of  things? 
The  different  observers  are  able  to  play  fast  and  loose 
with  it  without  ill  effects. 

Suppose  that  location  is,  I  will  not  say  entirely  a 
myth,  but  not  quite  the  definite  thing  it  is  made  out  to 
be  in  classical  physics;  that  the  Newtonian  idea  of 
location  contains  some  truth  and  some  padding,  and  it 
is  not  the  truth  but  the  padding  that  our  observers  are 
quarrelling  over.  That  would  explain  a  great  deal.  It 
would  explain,  for  instance,  why  all  the  forces  of  Nature 
seem  to  have  entered  into  a  conspiracy  to  prevent  our 
discovering  the  definite  location  of  any  object  (its  posi- 
tion in  the  "right"  frame  of  space)  ;  naturally  they 
cannot  reveal  it,  if  it  does  not  exist. 

This  thought  will  be  followed  up  in  the  next  chapter. 
Meanwhile  let  us  glance  back  over  the  arguments  that 
have  led  to  the  present  situation.  It  arises  from  the 
failure  of  our  much-trusted  measuring  scale,  a  failure 
which  we  can  infer  from  strong  experimental  evidence 
or  more  simply  as  an  inevitable  consequence  of  accepting 
the  electrical  theory  of  matter.  This  unforeseen  be- 
haviour is  a  constant  property  of  all  kinds  of  matter  and 
is  even  shared  by  optical  and  electrical  measuring  devices. 


SUMMARY  19 

Thus  it  is  not  betrayed  by  any  kind  of  discrepancy  in 
applying  the  usual  methods  of  measurement.  The  dis- 
crepancy is  revealed  when  we  change  the  standard 
motion  of  the  measuring  appliances,  e.g.  when  we  com- 
pare lengths  and  distances  as  measured  by  terrestrial 
observers  with  those  which  would  be  measured  by 
observers  on  a  planet  with  different  velocity.  Provision- 
ally we  shall  call  the  measured  lengths  which  contain 
this  discrepancy  "fictitious  lengths". 

According  to  the  Newtonian  scheme  length  is  definite 
and  unique;  and  each  observer  should  apply  corrections 
(dependent  on  his  motion)  to  reduce  his  fictitious  lengths 
to  the  unique  Newtonian  length.  But  to  this  there  are 
two  objections.  The  corrections  to  reduce  to  Newtonian 
length  are  indeterminate;  we  know  the  corrections 
necessary  to  reduce  our  own  fictitious  lengths  to  those 
measured  by  an  observer  with  any  other  prescribed 
motion,  but  there  is  no  criterion  for  deciding  which 
system  is  the  one  intended  in  the  Newtonian  scheme. 
Secondly,  the  whole  of  present-day  physics  has  been 
based  on  lengths  measured  by  terrestrial  observers 
without  this  correction,  so  that  whilst  its  assertions 
ostensibly  refer  to  Newtonian  lengths  they  have  actually 
been  proved  for  fictitious  lengths. 

The  FitzGerald  contraction  may  seem  a  little  thing 
to  bring  the  whole  structure  of  classical  physics  tumbling 
down.  But  few  indeed  are  the  experiments  contributing 
to  our  scientific  knowledge  which  would  not  be  invali- 
dated if  our  methods  of  measuring  lengths  were  funda- 
mentally unsound.  We  now  find  that  there  is  no 
guarantee  that  they  are  not  subject  to  a  systematic  kind 
of  error.  Worse  still  we  do  not  know  if  the  error 
occurs  or  not,  and  there  is  every  reason  to  presume 
that  it  is  impossible  to  know. 


Chapter  II 

RELATIVITY 

Einstein's  Principle.  The  modest  observer  mentioned  in 
the  first  chapter  was  faced  with  the  task  of  choosing 
between  a  number  of  frames  of  space  with  nothing  to 
guide  his  choice.  They  are  different  in  the  sense  that  they 
frame  the  material  objects  of  the  world,  including  the 
observer  himself,  differently;  but  they  are  indistinguish- 
able in  the  sense  that  the  world  as  framed  in  one  space 
conducts  itself  according  to  precisely  the  same  laws 
as  the  world  framed  in  another  space.  Owing  to  the 
accident  of  having  been  born  on  a  particular  planet 
our  observer  has  hitherto  unthinkingly  adopted  one  of 
the  frames;  but  he  realises  that  this  is  no  ground  for 
obstinately  asserting  that  it  must  be  the  right  frame. 
Which  is  the  right  frame? 

At  this  juncture  Einstein  comes  forward  with  a  sug- 
gestion— 

"You  are  seeking  a  frame  of  space  which  you  call 
the  right  frame.  In  what  does  its  rightness  consist?" 

You  are  standing  with  a  label  in  your  hand  before  a 
row  of  packages  all  precisely  similar.  You  are  worried 
because  there  is  nothing  to  help  you  decide  which  of 
the  packages  it  should  be  attached  to.  Look  at  the  label 
and  see  what  is  written  on  it.    Nothing. 

"Right"  as  applied  to  frames  of  space  is  a  blank  label. 
It  implies  that  there  is  something  distinguishing  a  right 
frame  from  a  wrong  frame;  but  when  we  ask  what  is 
this  distinguishing  property,  the  only  answer  we  receive 
is  "Rightness",  which  does  not  make  the  meaning  clearer 
or  convince  us  that  there  is  a  meaning. 

20 


EINSTEIN'S  PRINCIPLE  21 

I  am  prepared  to  admit  that  frames  of  space  in  spite 
of  their  present  resemblance  may  in  the  future  turn  out 
to  be  not  entirely  indistinguishable.  (I  deem  it  unlikely, 
but  I  do  not  exclude  it.)  The  future  physicist  might 
find  that  the  frame  belonging  to  Arcturus,  say,  is  unique 
as  regards  some  property  not  yet  known  to  science.  Then 
no  doubt  our  friend  with  the  label  will  hasten  to  affix 
it.  "I  told  you  so.  I  knew  I  meant  something 
when  I  talked  about  a  right  frame."  But  it  does  not 
seem  a  profitable  procedure  to  make  odd  noises  on 
the  off-chance  that  posterity  will  find  a  significance  to 
attribute  to  them.  To  those  who  now  harp  on  a  right 
frame  of  space  we  may  reply  in  the  words  of  Bottom  the 
weaver — 

"Who  would  set  his  wit  to  so  foolish  a  bird?  Who 
would  give  a  bird  the  lie,  though  he  cry  'cuckoo'  never 
so?" 

And  so  the  position  of  Einstein's  theory  is  that  the 
question  of  a  unique  right  frame  of  space  does  not  arise. 
There  is  a  frame  of  space  relative  to  a  terrestrial  ob- 
server, another  frame  relative  to  the  nebular  observers, 
others  relative  to  other  stars.  Frames  of  space  are  rela- 
tive. Distances,  lengths,  volumes — all  quantities  of 
space-reckoning  which  belong  to  the  frames — are  likewise 
relative.  A  distance  as  reckoned  by  an  observer  on  one 
star  is  as  good  as  the  distance  reckoned  by  an  observer 
on  another  star.  We  must  not  expect  them  to  agree; 
the  one  is  a  distance  relative,  to  one  frame,  the  other  is 
a  distance  relative  to  another  frame.  Absolute  distance, 
not  relative  to  some  special  frame,  is  meaningless. 

The  next  point  to  notice  is  that  the  other  quantities 
of  physics  go  along  with  the  frame  of  space,  so  that  they 
also  are  relative.  You  may  have  seen  one  of  those  tables 
of    "dimensions"    of    physical    quantities    showing    how 


22  RELATIVITY 

they  are  all  related  to  the  reckoning  of  length,  time  and 
mass.  If  you  alter  the  reckoning  of  length  you  alter  the 
reckoning  of  other  physical  quantities. 

Consider  an  electrically  charged  body  at  rest  on  the 
earth.  Since  it  is  at  rest  it  gives  an  electric  field  but  no 
magnetic  field.  But  for  the  nebular  physicist  it  is  a 
charged  body  moving  at  iooo  miles  a  second.  A  moving 
charge  constitutes  an  electric  current  which  in  accordance 
with  the  laws  of  electromagnetism  gives  rise  to  a  mag- 
netic field.  How  can  the  same  body  both  give  and 
not  give  a  magnetic  field?  On  the  classical  theory  we 
should  have  had  to  explain  one  of  these  results  as  an 
illusion.  (There  is  no  difficulty  in  doing  that;  only  there 
is  nothing  to  indicate  which  of  the  two  results  is  the  one 
to  be  explained  away.)  On  the  relativity  theory  both 
results  are  accepted.  Magnetic  fields  are  relative. 
There  is  no  magnetic  field  relative  to  the  terrestrial 
frame  of  space;  there  is  a  magnetic  field  relative  to 
the  nebular  frame  of  space.  The  nebular  physicist  will 
duly  detect  the  magnetic  field  with  his  instruments 
although  our  instruments  show  no  magnetic  field.  That 
is  because  he  uses  instruments  at  rest  on  his  planet  and 
we  use  instruments  at  rest  on  ours;  or  at  least  we  correct 
our  observations  to  accord  with  the  indications  of  instru- 
ments at  rest  in  our  respective  frames  of  space. 

Is  there  really  a  magnetic  field  or  not?  This  is  like 
the  previous  problem  of  the  square  and  the  oblong. 
There  is  one  specification  of  the  field  relative  to  one 
planet,  another  relative  to  another.  There  is  no  abso- 
lute specification. 

It  is  not  quite  true  to  say  that  all  the  physical  quan- 
tities are  relative  to  frames  of  space.  We  can  construct 
new  physical  quantities  by  multiplying,  dividing,  etc.; 
thus  we  multiply  mass  and  velocity  to  give  momentum, 


RELATIVE  AND  ABSOLUTE  QUANTITIES       23 

divide  energy  by  time  to  give  horse-power.  We  can  set 
ourselves  the  mathematical  problem  of  constructing  in 
this  way  quantities  which  shall  be  invariant,  that  is  to 
say,  shall  have  the  same  measure  whatever  frame  of 
space  may  be  used.  One  or  two  of  these  invariants 
turn  out  to  be  quantities  already  recognised  in  pre- 
relativity  physics;  "action"  and  "entropy"  are  the  best 
known.  Relativity  physics  is  especially  interested  in 
invariants,  and  it  has  discovered  and  named  a  few  more. 
It  is  a  common  mistake  to  suppose  that  Einstein's  theory 
of  relativity  asserts  that  everything  is  relative.  Actually 
it  says,  "There  are  absolute  things  in  the  world  but 
you  must  look  deeply  for  them.  The  things  that  first 
present  themselves  to  your  notice  are  for  the  most  part 
relative." 

Relative  and  Absolute  Quantities.  I  will  try  to  make 
clear  the  distinction  between  absolute  and  relative  quan- 
tities. Number  (of  discrete  individuals)  is  absolute.  It 
is  the  result  of  counting,  and  counting  is  an  absolute 
operation.  If  two  men  count  the  number  of  people  in 
this  room  and  reach  different  results,  one  of  them  must 
be  wrong. 

The  measurement  of  distance  is  not  an  absolute 
operation.  It  is  possible  for  two  men  to  measure  the 
same  distance  and  reach  different  results,  and  yet  neither 
of  them  be  wrong. 

I  mark  two  dots  on  the^  blackboard  and  ask  two 
students  to  measure  very  accurately  the  distance  between 
them.  In  order  that  there  may  be  no  possible  doubt  as 
to  what  I  mean  by  distance  I  give  them  elaborate 
instructions  as  to  the  standard  to  be  used  and  the  pre- 
cautions necessary  to  obtain  an  accurate  measurement 
of  distance.     They  bring  me  results  which  differ.     I  ask 


24  RELATIVITY 

them  to  compare  notes  to  find  out  which  of  them  is 
wrong,  and  why?  Presently  they  return  and  say:  "It 
was  your  fault  because  in  one  respect  your  instructions 
were  not  explicit.  You  did  not  mention  what  motion 
the  scale  should  have  when  it  was  being  used."  One 
of  them  without  thinking  much  about  the  matter  had 
kept  the  scale  at  rest  on  the  earth.  The  other  had 
reflected  that  the  earth  was  a  very  insignificant  planet  of 
which  the  Professor  had  a  low  opinion.  He  thought  it 
would  be  only  reasonable  to  choose  some  more  impor- 
tant body  to  regulate  the  motion  of  the  scale,  and  so  he 
had  given  it  a  motion  agreeing  with  that  of  the  enor- 
mous star  Betelgeuse.  Naturally  the  FitzGerald  contrac- 
tion of  the  scale  accounted  for  the  difference  of  results. 

I  am  disinclined  to  accept  this  excuse.  I  say  severely, 
"It  is  all  nonsense  dragging  in  the  earth  or  Betel- 
geuse or  any  other  body.  You  do  not  require  any 
standard  external  to  the  problem.  I  told  you  to  measure 
the  distance  of  two  points  on  the  blackboard;  you  should 
have  made  the  motion  of  the  scale  agree  with  that  of 
the  blackboard.  Surely  it  is  commonsense  to  make  your 
measuring  scale  move  with  what  you  are  measuring. 
Remember  that  next  time." 

A  few  days  later  I  ask  them  to  measure  the  wave- 
length of  sodium  light — the  distance  from  crest  to  crest 
of  the  light  waves.  They  do  so  and  return  in  triumphal 
agreement:  ''The  wave-length  is  infinite".  I  point  out 
to  them  that  this  does  not  agree  with  the  result  given 
in  the  book  (.000059  cm.).  "Yes",  they  reply,  uwe 
noticed  that;  but  the  man  in  the  book  did  not  do  it 
right.  You  told  us  always  to  make  the  measuring  scale 
move  with  the  thing  to  be  measured.  So  at  great  trouble 
and  expense  we  sent  our  scales  hurtling  through  the 
laboratory  at  the  same  speed  as  the  light."   At  this  speed 


RELATIVE  AND  ABSOLUTE  QUANTITIES       25 

the  FitzGerald  contraction  is  infinite,  the  metre  rods 
contract  to  nothing,  and  so  it  takes  an  infinite  number 
of  them  to  fill  up  the  interval  from  crest  to  crest  of  the 
waves. 

My  supplementary  rule  was  in  a  way  quite  a  good 
rule;  it  would  always  give  something  absolute — some- 
thing on  which  they  would  necessarily  agree.  Only 
unfortunately  it  would  not  give  the  length  or  distance. 
When  we  ask  whether  distance  is  absolute  or  relative, 
we  must  not  first  make  up  our  minds  that  it  ought  to 
be  absolute  and  then  change  the  current  significance  of 
the  term  to  make  it  so. 

Nor  can  we  altogether  blame  our  predecessors  for 
having  stupidly  made  the  word  "distance"  mean  some- 
thing relative  when  they  might  have  applied  it  to  a 
result  of  spatial  measurement  which  was  absolute  and 
unambiguous.  The  suggested  supplementary  rule  has 
one  drawback.  We  often  have  to  consider  a  system 
containing  a  number  of  bodies  with  different  motions; 
it  would  be  inconvenient  to  have  to  measure  each  body 
with  apparatus  in  a  different  state  of  motion,  and  we 
should  get  into  a  terrible  muddle  in  trying  to  fit  the 
different  measures  together.  Our  predecessors  were 
wise  in  referring  all  distances  to  a  single  frame  of  space, 
even  though  their  expectation  that  such  distances  would 
be  absolute  has  not  been  fulfilled. 

As  for  the  absolute  quantity  given  by  the  proposed 
supplementary  rule,  we  may  set  it  alongside  distances 
relative  to  the  earth  and  distances  relative  to  Betelgeuse, 
etc.,  as  a  quantity  of  some  interest  to  study.  It  is  called 
"proper-distance".  Perhaps  you  feel  a  relief  at  getting 
hold  of  something  absolute  and  would  wish  to  follow 
it  up.  Excellent.  But  remember  this  will  lead  you  away 
from  the  classical  scheme  of  physics  which  has  chosen 


26  RELATIVITY 

the  relative  distances  to  build  on.  The  quest  of  the 
absolute  leads  into  the   four-dimensional  world. 

A  more  familiar  example  of  a  relative  quantity  is 
"direction"  of  an  object.  There  is  a  direction  of  Cam- 
bridge relative  to  Edinburgh  and  another  direction  rela- 
tive to  London,  and  so  on.  It  never  occurs  to  us  to 
think  of  this  as  a  discrepancy,  or  to  suppose  that  there 
must  be  some  direction  of  Cambridge  (at  present  undis- 
coverable)  which  is  absolute.  The  idea  that  there  ought 
to  be  an  absolute  distance  between  two  points  contains 
the  same  kind  of  fallacy.  There  is,  of  course,  a  differ- 
ence of  detail;  the  relative  direction  above  mentioned  is 
relative  to  a  particular  position  of  the  observer,  whereas 
the  relative  distance  is  relative  to  a  particular  velocity 
of  the  observer.  We  can  change  position  freely  and 
so  introduce  large  changes  of  relative  direction;  but 
we  cannot  change  velocity  appreciably — the  300  miles 
an  hour  attainable  by  our  fastest  devices  being  too 
insignificant  to  count.  Consequently  the  relativity  of 
distance  is  not  a  matter  of  common  experience  as  the 
relativity  of  direction  is.  That  is  why  we  have  unfor- 
tunately a  rooted  impression  in  our  minds  that  distance 
ought  to  be  absolute. 

A  very  homely  illustration  of  a  relative  quantity  is 
afforded  by  the  pound  sterling.  Whatever  may  have 
been  the  correct  theoretical  view,  the  man  in  the  street 
until  very  recently  regarded  a  pound  as  an  absolute 
amount  of  wealth.  But  dire  experience  has  now  con- 
vinced us  all  of  its  relativity.  At  first  we  used  to  cling 
to  the  idea  that  there  ought  to  be  an  absolute  pound 
and  struggle  to  express  the  situation  in  paradoxical  state- 
ments— the  pound  had  really  become  seven-and-six- 
pence.  But  we  have  grown  accustomed  to  the  situation 
and    continue   to    reckon   wealth    in   pounds    as   before, 


NATURE'S  PLAN  OF  STRUCTURE  27 

merely  recognising  that  the  pound  is  relative  and  there- 
fore must  not  be  expected  to  have  those  properties  that 
we  had  attributed  to  it  in  the  belief  that  it  was  absolute. 
You  can  form  some  idea  of  the  essential  difference  in 
the  outlook  of  physics  before  and  after  Einstein's 
principle  of  relativity  by  comparing  it  with  the  difference 
in  economic  theory  which  comes  from  recognising  the 
•relativity  of  value  of  money.  I  suppose  that  in  stable 
times  the  practical  consequences  of  this  relativity  are 
manifested  chiefly  in  the  minute  fluctuations  of  foreign 
exchanges,  which  may  be  compared  with  the  minute 
changes  of  length  affecting  delicate  experiments  like  the 
Michelson-Morley  experiment.  Occasionally  the  con- 
sequences may  be  more  sensational — a  mark-exchange 
soaring  to  billions,  a  high-speed  8  particle  contracting 
to  a  third  of  its  radius.  But  it  is  not  these  casual  mani- 
festations which  are  the  main  outcome.  Clearly  an 
economist  who  believes  in  the  absoluteness  of  the  pound 
has  not  grasped  the  rudiments  of  his  subject.  Similarly 
if  we  have  conceived  the  physical  world  as  intrinsically 
constituted  out  of  those  distances,  forces  and  masses 
which  are  now  seen  to  have  reference  only  to  our  own 
special  reference  frame,  we  are  far  from  a  proper  under- 
standing of  the  nature  of  things. 

Nature's  Plan  of  Structure.  Let  us  now  return  to  the 
observer  who  was  so  anxious  to  pick  out  a  "right" 
frame  of  space.  I  suppose  that  what  he  had  in  mind 
was  to  find  Nature's  own  frame — the  frame  on  which 
Nature  based  her  calculations  when  she  poised  the 
planets  under  the  law  of  gravity,  or  the  reckoning  of 
symmetry  which  she  used  when  she  turned  the  electrons 
on  her  lathe.  But  Nature  has  been  too  subtle  for  him; 
she  has  not  left  anything  to  betray  the  frame  which  she 


28  RELATIVITY 

used.  Or  perhaps  the  concealment  is  not  any  particular 
subtlety;  she  may  have  done  her  work  without  employing 
a  frame  of  space.    Let  me  tell  you  a  parable. 

There  was  once  an  archaeologist  who  used  to  com- 
pute the  dates  of  ancient  temples  from  their  orientation. 
He  found  that  they  were  aligned  with  respect  to  the 
rising  of  particular  stars.  Owing  to  precession  the 
star  no  longer  rises  in  the  original  line,  but  the  date 
when  it  was  rising  in  the  line  of  the  temple  can  be 
calculated,  and  hence  the  epoch  of  construction  of  the 
temple  is  discovered.  But  there  was  one  tribe  for 
which  this  method  would  not  work;  they  had  built  only 
circular  temples.  To  the  archaeologist  this  seemed  a 
manifestation  of  extraordinary  subtlety  on  their  part; 
they  had  hit  on  a  device  which  would  conceal  entirely 
the  date  when  their  temples  were  constructed.  One 
critic,  however,  made  the  ribald  suggestion  that  per- 
haps this  particular  tribe  was  not  enthusiastic  about 
astronomy. 

Like  the  critic  I  do  not  think  Nature  has  been  par- 
ticularly subtle  in  concealing  which  frame  she  prefers. 
It  is  just  that  she  is  not  enthusiastic  about  frames  of 
space.  They  are  a  method  of  partition  which  wTe  have 
found  useful  for  reckoning,  but  they  play  no  part  in 
the  architecture  of  the  universe.  Surely  it  is  absurd  to 
suppose  that  the  universe  is  planned  in  such  a  way  as  to 
conceal  its  plan.  It  is  like  the  schemes  of  the  White 
Knight — 

But  I  was  thinking  of  a  plan 

To  dye  one's  whiskers  green, 

And  always  use  so  large  a  fan 

That  they  could  not  be  seen. 

If  this  is  so  we  shall  have  to  sweep  away  the  frames 
of   space  before  we   can  see   Nature's  plan  in   its   real 


NATURE'S  PLAN  OF  STRUCTURE  29 

significance.  She  herself  has  paid  no  attention  to  them, 
and  they  can  only  obscure  the  simplicity  of  her  scheme. 
I  do  not  mean  to  suggest  that  we  should  entirely  rewrite 
physics,  eliminating  all  reference  to  frames  of  space  or 
any  quantities  referred  to  them;  science  has  many  tasks 
to  perform,  besides  that  of  apprehending  the  ultimate 
plan  of  structure  of  the  world.  But  if  we  do  wish  to 
have  insight  on  this  latter  point,  then  the  first  step  is  to 
make  an  escape  from  the  irrelevant  space-frames. 

This  will  involve  a  great  change  from  classical  con- 
ceptions, and  important  developments  will  follow  from 
our  change  of  attitude.  For  example,  it  is  known  that 
both  gravitation  and  electric  force  follow  approximately 
the  law  of  inverse-square  of  the  distance.  This  law 
appeals  strongly  to  us  by  its  simplicity;  not  only  is  it 
mathematically  simple  but  it  corresponds  very  naturally 
with  the  weakening  of  an  effect  by  spreading  out  in 
three  dimensions.  We  suspect  therefore  that  it  is 
likely  to  be  the  exact  law  of  gravitational  and  electric 
fields.  But  although  it  is  simple  for  us  it  is  far  from 
simple  for  Nature.  Distance  refers  to  a  space-frame; 
it  is  different  according  to  the  frame  chosen.  We  cannot 
make  sense  of  the  law  of  inverse-square  of  the  distance 
unless  we  have  first  fixed  on  a  frame  of  space;  but 
Nature  has  not  fixed  on  any  one  frame.  Even  if  by 
some  self-compensation  the  law  worked  out  so  as  to  give 
the  same  observable  consequences  whatever  space-frame 
we  might  happen  to  choose  (which  it  does  not)  we  should 
still  be  misapprehending  its  real  mode  of  operation.  In 
chapter  VI  we  shall  try  to  gain  a  new  insight  into  the 
law  (which  for  most  practical  applications  is  so  nearly 
expressed  by  the  inverse-square)  and  obtain  a  picture 
of  its  working  which  does  not  drag  in  an  irrelevant  frame 
of    space.      The    recognition    of    relativity    leads    us    to 


30  RELATIVITY 

seek  a  new  way  of  unravelling  the  complexity  of  natural 
phenomena. 

Velocity  through  the  Aether.  The  theory  of  relativity  is 
evidently  bound  up  with  the  impossibility  of  detecting 
absolute  velocity;  if  in  our  quarrel  with  the  nebular 
physicists  one  of  us  had  been  able  to  claim  to  be 
absolutely  at  rest,  that  would  be  sufficient  reason  for 
preferring  the  corresponding  frame.  This  has  some- 
thing in  common  with  the  well-known  philosophic  belief 
that  motion  must  necessarily  be  relative.  Motion  is 
change  of  position  relative  to  something-,  if  we  try  to 
think  of  change  of  position  relative  to  nothing  the  whole 
conception  fades  away.  But  this  does  not  completely 
settle  the  physical  problem.  In  physics  we  should  not 
be  quite  so  scrupulous  as  to  the  use  of  the  word  absolute. 
Motion  with  respect  to  aether  or  to  any  universally  sig- 
nificant frame  would  be  called  absolute. 

No  aethereal  frame  has  been  found.  We  can  only 
discover  motion  relative  to  the  material  landmarks 
scattered  casually  about  the  world;  motion  with  respect 
to  the  universal  ocean  of  aether  eludes  us.  We  say, 
"Let  V  be  the  velocity  of  a  body  through  the  aether", 
and  form  the  various  electromagnetic  equations  in  which 
V  is  scattered  liberally.  Then  we  insert  the  observed 
values,  and  try  to  eliminate  everything  that  is  unknown 
except  V.  The  solution  goes  on  famously;  but  just  as 
we  have  got  rid  of  the  other  unknowns,  behold!  V  dis- 
appears as  well,  and  we  are  left  with  the  indisputable 
but  irritating  conclusion — 

This  is  a  favourite  device  that  mathematical  equations 
resort  to,  when  we  propound  stupid  questions.  If  we 
tried  to  find  the  latitude  and  longitude  of  a  point  north- 


VELOCITY  THROUGH  THE  AETHER  31 

east  from  the  north  pole  we  should  probably  receive 
the  same  mathematical  answer.  "Velocity  through 
aether"  is  as  meaningless  as  "north-east  from  the  north 
pole". 

This  does  not  mean  that  the  aether  is  abolished.  We 
need  an  aether.  The  physical  world  is  not  to  be  analysed 
into  isolated  particles  of  matter  or  electricity  with 
featureless  interspace.  We  have  to  attribute  as  much 
character  to  the  interspace  as  to  the  particles,  and  in 
present-day  physics  quite  an  army  of  symbols  is  required 
to  describe  what  is  going  on  in  the  interspace.  We 
postulate  aether  to  bear  the  characters  of  the  interspace 
as  we  postulate  matter  or  electricity  to  bear  the  charac- 
ters of  the  particles.  Perhaps  a  philosopher  might  ques- 
tion whether  it  is  not  possible  to  admit  the  characters 
alone  without  picturing  anything  to  support  them — thus 
doing  away  with  aether  and  matter  at  one  stroke.  But 
that  is  rather  beside  the  point. 

In  the  last  century  it  was  widely  believed  that  aether 
was  a  kind  of  matter,  having  properties  such  as  mass, 
rigidity,  motion,  like  ordinary  matter.  It  would  be 
difficult  to  say  when  this  view  died  out.  It  probably 
lingered  longer  in  England  than  on  the  continent,  but 
I  think  that  even  here  it  had  ceased  to  be  the  orthodox 
view  some  years  before  the  advent  of  the  relativity 
theory.  Logically  it  was  abandoned  by  the  numerous 
nineteenth-century  investigators  who  regarded  matter 
as  vortices,  knots,  squirts,  etc.,  in  the  aether;  for  clearly 
they  could  not  have  supposed  that  aether  consisted  of 
vortices  in  the  aether.  But  it  may  not  be  safe  to  assume 
that  the  authorities  in  question  were  logical. 

Nowadays  it  is  agreed  that  aether  is  not  a  kind  of 
matter.  Being  non-material,  its  properties  are  sui  generis. 
We  must  determine  them  by  experiment;  and  since  we 


32  RELATIVITY 

have  no  ground  for  any  preconception,  the  experimental 
conclusions  can  be  accepted  without  surprise  or  mis- 
giving. Characters  such  as  mass  and  rigidity  which  we 
meet  with  in  matter  will  naturally  be  absent  in  aether; 
but  the  aether  will  have  new  and  definite  characters  of 
its  own.  In  a  material  ocean  we  can  say  that  a  particu- 
lar particle  of  water  which  was  here  a  few  moments  ago 
is  now  over  there;  there  is  no  corresponding  assertion 
that  can  be  made  about  the  aether.  If  you  have  been 
thinking  of  the  aether  in  a  way  which  takes  for  granted 
this  property  of  permanent  identification  of  its  particles, 
you  must  revise  your  conception  in  accordance  with  the 
modern  evidence.  We  cannot  find  our  velocity  through 
the  aether;  we  cannot  say  whether  the  aether  now  in  this 
room  is  flowing  out  through  the  north  wall  or  the  south 
wall.  The  question  would  have  a  meaning  for  a  mate- 
rial ocean,  but  there  is  no  reason  to  expect  it  to  have  a 
meaning  for  the  non-material  ocean  of  aether. 

The  aether  itself  is  as  much  to  the  fore  as  ever  it  was, 
in  our  present  scheme  of  the  world.  But  velocity  through 
aether  has  been  found  to  resemble  that  elusive  lady 
Mrs.  Harris;  and  Einstein  has  inspired  us  with  the 
daring  scepticism — "I  don't  believe  there's  no  sich  a 
person". 

Is  the  FitzGerald  Contraction  Real?  I  am  often  asked 
whether  the  FitzGerald  contraction  really  occurs.  It 
was  introduced  in  the  first  chapter  before  the  idea  of 
relativity  was  mentioned,  and  perhaps  it  is  not  quite 
clear  what  has  become  of  it  now  that  the  theory  of 
relativity  has  given  us  a  new  conception  of  what  is  going 
on  in  the  world.  Naturally  my  first  chapter,  which 
describes  the  phenomena  according  to  the  ideas  of 
classical  physics  in  order  to  show  the  need   for  a  new 


IS  FITZGERALD  CONTRACTION  REAL?        33 

theory,    contains    many    statements    which    we    should 
express  differently  in  relativity  physics. 

Is  it  really  true  that  a  moving  rod  becomes  shortened 
in  the  direction  of  its  motion?  It  is  not  altogether  easy 
to  give  a  plain  answer.  I  think  we  often  draw  a  dis- 
tinction between  what  is  true  and  what  is  really  true.  A 
statement  which  does  not  profess  to  deal  with  anything 
except  appearances  may  be  true;  a  statement  which  is 
not  only  true  but  deals  with  the  realities  beneath  the 
appearances  is  really  true. 

You  receive  a  balance-sheet  from  a  public  company 
and  observe  that  the  assets  amount  to  such  and  such  a 
figure.  Is  this  true?  Certainly;  it  is  certified  by  a 
chartered  accountant.  But  is  it  really  true?  Many 
questions  arise;  the  real  values  of  items  are  often  very 
different  from  those  which  figure  in  the  balance-sheet. 
I  am  not  especially  referring  to  fraudulent  companies. 
There  is  a  blessed  phrase  "hidden  reserves";  and  gen- 
erally speaking  the  more  respectable  the  company  the 
more  widely  does  its  balance-sheet  deviate  from  reality. 
This  is  called  sound  finance.  But  apart  from  deliberate 
use  of  the  balance-sheet  to  conceal  the  actual  situation, 
it  is  not  well  adapted  for  exhibiting  realities,  because 
the  main  function  of  a  balance-sheet  is  to  balance 
and  everything  else  has  to  be  subordinated  to  that 
end. 

The  physicist  who  uses  a  frame  of  space  has  to 
account  for  every  millimetre  of  space — in  fact  to  draw 
up  a  balance-sheet,  and  make  it  balance.  Usually  there 
is  not  much  difficulty.  But  suppose  that  he  happens  to 
be  concerned  with  a  man  travelling  at  161^000  miles 
a  second.  The  man  is  an  ordinary  6-foot  man.  So  far 
as  reality  is  concerned  the  proper  entry  in  the  balance- 
sheet  would  appear  to  be  6  feet.     But  then  the  balance- 


34  RELATIVITY 

sheet  would  not  balance.  In  accounting  for  the  rest  of 
space  there  is  left  only  3  feet  between  the  crown  of  his 
head  and  the  soles  of  his  boots.  His  balance-sheet 
length  is  therefore  "written  down"  to  3  feet. 

The  writing-down  of  lengths  for  balance-sheet  pur- 
poses is  the  FitzGerald  contraction.  The  shortening  of 
the  moving  rod  is  true,  but  it  is  not  really  true.  It  is  not 
a  statement  about  reality  (the  absolute)  but  it  is  a  true 
statement  about  appearances  in  our  frame  of  reference.* 
An  object  has  different  lengths  in  the  different  space- 
frames,  and  any  6-foot  man  will  have  a  length  3  feet  in 
some  frame  or  other.  The  statement  that  the  length  of 
the  rapid  traveller  is  3  feet  is  true,  but  it  does  not  indicate 
any  special  peculiarity  about  the  man;  it  only  indicates 
that  our  adopted  frame  is  the  one  in  which  his  length  is 
3  feet.  If  it  hadn't  been  ours,  it  would  have  been  some- 
one else's. 

Perhaps  you  will  think  we  ought  to  alter  our  method 
of  keeping  the  accounts  of  space  so  as  to  make  them 
directly  represent  the  realities.  That  would  be  going  to 
a  lot  of  trouble  to  provide  for  what  are  after  all  rather 
rare  transactions.  But  as  a  matter  of  fact  we  have 
managed  to  meet  your  desire.  Thanks  to  Minkowski 
a  way  of  keeping  accounts  has  been  found  which 
exhibits  realities  (absolute  things)  and  balances.  There 
has  been  no  great  rush  to  adopt  it  for  ordinary  purposes 
because  it  is  a  four-dimensional  balance-sheet. 

Let  us  take  a  last  glance  back  before  we  plunge  into 

*The  proper-length  (p.  25)  is  unaltered;  but  the  relative  length  is 
shortened.  We  have  already  seen  that  the  word  "length"  as  currently- 
used  refers  to  relative  length,  and  in  confirming  the  statement  that  the 
moving  rod  changes  its  length  we  are,  of  course,  assuming  that  the  word 
is  used  with  its  current  meaning. 


SUMMARY  35 

four  dimensions.  We  have  been  confronted  with  some- 
thing not  contemplated  in  classical  physics — a  multi- 
plicity of  frames  of  space,  each  one  as  good  as  any 
other.  And  in  place  of  a  distance,  magnetic  force, 
acceleration,  etc.,  which  according  to  classical  ideas 
must  necessarily  be  definite  and  unique,  we  are  con- 
fronted with  different  distances,  etc.,  corresponding  to 
the  different  frames,  with  no  ground  for  making  a  choice 
between  them.  Our  simple  solution  has  been  to  give 
up  the  idea  that  one  of  these  is  right  and  that  the  others 
are  spurious  imitations,  and  to  accept  them  en  bloc;  so 
that  distance,  magnetic  force,  acceleration,  etc.,  are 
relative  quantities,  comparable  with  other  relative  quan- 
tities already  known  to  us  such  as  direction  or  velocity. 
In  the  main  this  leaves  the  structure  of  our  physical 
knowledge  unaltered;  only  we  must  give  up  certain 
expectations  as  to  the  behaviour  of  these  quantities,  and 
certain  tacit  assumptions  which  were  based  on  the  belief 
that  they  are  absolute.  In  particular  a  law  of  Nature 
which  seemed  simple  and  appropriate  for  absolute  quan- 
tities may  be  quite  inapplicable  to  relative  quantities  and 
therefore  require  some  tinkering.  Whilst  the  structure  of 
our  physical  knowledge  is  not  much  affected,  the  change 
in  the  underlying  conceptions  is  radical.  We  have  trav- 
elled far  from  the  old  standpoint  which  demanded 
mechanical  models  of  everything  in  Nature,  seeing  that 
we  do  not  now  admit  even  a  definite  unique  distance 
between  two  points.  The  relativity  of  the  current  scheme 
of  physics  invites  us  to  search  deeper  and  find  the  abso- 
lute scheme  underlying  it,  so  that  we  may  see  the  world 
in  a  truer  perspective. 


Chapter  III 

TIME 

Astronomer  Royal's  Time.  I  have  sometimes  thought  it 
would  be  very  entertaining  to  hear  a  discussion  between 
the  Astronomer  Royal  and,  let  us  say,  Prof.  Bergson  on 
the  nature  of  time.  Prof.  Bergson's  authority  on  the 
subject  is  well  known;  and  I  may  remind  you  that  the 
Astronomer  Royal  is  entrusted  with  the  duty  of  finding 
out  time  for  our  everyday  use,  so  presumably  he  has 
some  idea  of  what  he  has  to  find.  I  must  date  the 
discussion  some  twenty  years  back,  before  the  spread  of 
Einstein's  ideas  brought  about  a  rapprochement.  There 
would  then  probably  have  been  a  keen  disagreement, 
and  I  rather  think  that  the  philosopher  would  have  had 
the  best  of  the  verbal  argument.  After  showing  that 
the  Astronomer  Royal's  idea  of  time  was  quite  non- 
sensical, Prof.  Bergson  would  probably  end  the  dis- 
cussion by  looking  at  his  watch  and  rushing  off  to  catch 
a  train  which  was  starting  by  the  Astronomer  Royal's 
time. 

Whatever  may  be  time  de  ]ure}  the  Astronomer 
Royal's  time  is  time  de  facto.  His  time  permeates  every 
corner  of  physics.  It  stands  in  no  need  of  logical  de- 
fence; it  is  in  the  much  stronger  position  of  a  vested 
interest.  It  has  been  woven  into  the  structure  of  the 
classical  physical  scheme.  "Time"  in  physics  means 
Astronomer  Royal's  time.  You  may  be  aware  that  it  is 
revealed  to  us  in  Einstein's  theory  that  time  and  space 
are  mixed  up  in  a  rather  strange  way.  This  is  a  great 
stumbling-block  to  the  beginner.  He  is  inclined  to  say, 
"That  is  impossible.     I  feel  it  in  my  bones  that  time  and 

36 


ASTRONOMER  ROYAL'S  TIME  37 

space  must  be  of  entirely  different  nature.  They  cannot 
possibly  be  mixed  up."  The  Astronomer  Royal  com- 
placently retorts,  "It  is  not  impossible.  /  have  mixed 
them  up."  Well,  that  settles  it.  If  the  Astronomer 
Royal  has  mixed  them,  then  his  mixture  will  be  the 
groundwork  of  present-day  physics. 

We  have  to  distinguish  two  questions  which  are  not 
necessarily  identical.  First,  what  is  the  true  nature  of 
time?  Second,  what  is  the  nature  of  that  quantity  which 
has  under  the  name  of  time  become  a  fundamental  part 
of  the  structure  of  classical  physics?  By  long  history 
of  experiment  and  theory  the  results  of  physical  inves- 
tigation have  been  woven  into  a  scheme  which  has  on 
the  whole  proved  wonderfully  successful.  Time — the 
Astronomer  Royal's  time — has  its  importance  from  the 
fact  that  it  is  a  constituent  of  that  scheme,  the  binding 
material  or  mortar  of  it.  That  importance  is  not  les- 
sened if  it  should  prove  to  be  only  imperfectly  repre- 
sentative of  the  time  familiar  to  our  consciousness.  We 
therefore  give  priority  to  the  second  question. 

But  I  may  add  that  Einstein's  theory,  having  cleared 
up  the  second  question,  having  found  that  physical 
time  is  incongruously  mixed  with  space,  is  able  to  pass 
on  to  the  first  question.  There  is  a  quantity,  unrecog- 
nised in  pre-relativity  physics,  which  more  directly 
represents  the  time  known  to  consciousness.  This  is 
called  proper-time  or  interval.  It  is  definitely  separate 
from  and  unlike  proper-space.  Your  protest  in  the 
name  of  commonsense  against  a  mixing  of  time  and 
space  is  a  feeling  which  I  desire  to  encourage.  Time  and 
space  ought  to  be  separated.  The  current  representa- 
tion of  the  enduring  world  as  a  three-dimensional  space 
leaping  from  instant  to  instant  through  time  is  an 
unsuccessful  attempt  to  separate  them.     Come  back  with 


38  TIME 

me  into  the  virginal  four-dimensional  world  and  we  will 
carve  it  anew  on  a  plan  which  keeps  them  entirely 
distinct.  We  can  then  resurrect  the  almost  forgotten 
time  of  consciousness  and  find  that  it  has  a  gratifying 
importance  in  the  absolute  scheme  of  Nature. 

But  first  let  us  try  to  understand  why  physical  time 
has  come  to  deviate  from  time  as  immediately  perceived. 
We  have  jumped  to  certain  conclusions  about  time  and 
have  come  to  regard  them  almost  as  axiomatic,  although 
they  are  not  really  justified  by  anything  in  our  immediate 
perception  of  time.     Here  is  one  of  them. 

If  two  people  meet  twice  they  must  have  lived  the 
same  time  between  the  two  meetings,  even  if  one  of 
them  has  travelled  to  a  distant  part  of  the  universe  and 
back  in  the  interim. 

An  absurdly  impossible  experiment,  you  will  say. 
Quite  so;  it  is  outside  all  experience.  Therefore,  may 
I  suggest  that  you  are  not  appealing  to  your  experience 
of  time  when  you  object  to  a  theory  which  denies  the 
above  statement?  And  yet  if  the  question  is  pressed 
most  people  would  answer  impatiently  that  of  course 
the  statement  is  true.  They  have  formed  a  notion  of 
time  rolling  on  outside  us  in  a  way  which  makes  this 
seem  inevitable.  They  do  not  ask  themselves  whether 
this  conclusion  is  warranted  by  anything  in  their  actual 
experience  of  time. 

Although  we  cannot  try  the  experiment  of  sending  a 
man  to  another  part  of  the  universe,  we  have  enough 
scientific  knowledge  to  compute  the  rates  of  atomic  and 
other  physical  processes  in  a  body  at  rest  and  a  body 
travelling  rapidly.  We  can  say  definitely  that  the  bodily 
processes  in  the  traveller  occur  more  slowly  than  the 
corresponding  processes  in  the  man  at  rest  (i.e.  more 
slowly  according  to  the  Astronomer  Royal's  time).    This 


ASTRONOMER  ROYAL'S  TIME  39 

is  not  particularly  mysterious;  it  is  well  known  both 
from  theory  and  experiment  that  the  mass  or  inertia  of 
matter  increases  when  the  velocity  increases.  The  re- 
tardation is  a  natural  consequence  of  the  greater  inertia. 
Thus  so  far  as  bodily  processes  are  concerned  the  fast- 
moving  traveller  lives  more  slowly.  His  cycle  of  diges- 
tion and  fatigue;  the  rate  of  muscular  response  to  stim- 
ulus; the  development  of  his  body  from  youth  to  age; 
the  material  processes  in  his  brain  which  must  more  or 
less  keep  step  with  the  passage  of  thoughts  and  emo- 
tions; the  watch  which  ticks  in  his  waistcoat  pocket;  all 
these  must  be  slowed  down  in  the  same  ratio.  If  the 
speed  of  travel  is  very  great  we  may  find  that,  whilst 
the  stay-at-home  individual  has  aged  70  years,  the  trav- 
eller has  aged  1  year.  He  has  only  found  appetite  for 
365  breakfasts,  lunches,  etc.;  his  intellect,  clogged  by  a 
slow-moving  brain,  has  only  traversed  the  amount  of 
thought  appropriate  to  one  year  of  terrestrial  life.  His 
watch,  which  gives  a  more  accurate  and  scientific  reck- 
oning, confirms  this.  Judging  by  the  time  which  con- 
sciousness attempts  to  measure  after  its  own  rough 
fashion — and,  I  repeat,  this  is  the  only  reckoning  of  time 
which  we  have  a  right  to  expect  to  be  distinct  from 
space — the  two  men  have  not  lived  the  same  time 
between  the  two  meetings. 

Reference  to  time  as  estimated  by  consciousness  is 
complicated  by  the  fact  that  the  reckoning  is  very  erratic. 
"I'D  tell  you  who  Time  ambles  withal,  who  Time  trots 
withal,  who  Time  gallops  withal,  and  who  he  stands 
still  withal."  I  have  not  been  referring  to  these  sub- 
jective variations.  I  do  not  very  willingly  drag  in 
so  unsatisfactory  a  time-keeper;  only  I  have  to  deal 
with  the  critic  who  tells  me  what  "he  feels  in  his  bones" 
about  time,  and  I  would  point  out  to  him  that  the  basis 


40  TIME 

of  that  feeling  is  time  lived,  which  we  have  just  seen 
may  be  70  years  for  one  individual  and  1  year  for 
another  between  their  two  meetings.  We  can  reckon 
"time  lived'5  quite  scientifically,  e.g.  by  a  watch  travel- 
ling with  the  individual  concerned  and  sharing  his 
changes  of  inertia  with  velocity.  But  there  are  obvious 
drawbacks  to  the  general  adoption  of  "time  lived".  It 
might  be  useful  for  each  individual  to  have  a  private 
time  exactly  proportioned  to  his  time  lived;  but  it  would 
be  extremely  inconvenient  for  making  appointments. 
Therefore  the  Astronomer  Royal  has  adopted  a  uni- 
versal time-reckoning  which  does  not  follow  at  all  strictly 
the  time  lived.  According  to  it  the  time-lapse  does  not 
depend  on  how  the  object  under  consideration  has 
moved  in  the  meanwhile.  I  admit  that  this  reckoning 
is  a  little  hard  on  our  returned  traveller,  who  will  be 
counted  by  it  as  an  octogenarian  although  he  is  to  all 
appearances  still  a  boy  in  his  teens.  But  sacrifices  must 
be  made  for  the  general  benefit.  In  practice  we  have 
not  to  deal  with  human  beings  travelling  at  any  great 
speed;  but  we  have  to  deal  with  atoms  and  electrons 
travelling  at  terrific  speed,  so  that  the  question  of  pri- 
vate time-reckoning  versus  general  time-reckoning  is  a 
very  practical  one. 

Thus  in  physical  time  (or  Astronomer  Royal's  time) 
two  people  are  deemed  to  have  lived  the  same  time 
between  two  meetings,  whether  or  not  that  accords  with 
their  actual  experience.  The  consequent  deviation  from 
the  time  of  experience  is  responsible  for  the  mixing 
up  of  time  and  space,  which,  of  course,  would  be 
impossible  if  the  time  of  direct  experience  had  been 
rigidly  adhered  to.  Physical  time  is,  like  space,  a  kind 
of  frame  in  which  we  locate  the  events  of  the  external 
world.     We  are  now  going  to  consider  how  in  practice 


LOCATION  OF  EVENTS 


4i 


external  events  are  located  in  a  frame  of  space  and  time. 
We  have  seen  that  there  is  an  infinite  choice  of  alter- 
native frames;  so,  to  be  quite  explicit,  I  will  tell  you 
how  /  locate  events  in  my  frame. 

Location  of  Events,  In  Fig.  1  you  see  a  collection  of 
events,  indicated  by  circles.     They  are  not  at  present  in 


FUTURE 
O 

u 

Ld 

cc 

q: 

LxJ 

O 

©HERE-NOW 

O 

O 

Ld 

I 

X 

Ld 

0 

Ld 

if> 

O 

<o 

-J 

^m^ 

^+^ 

-J 

Ld 

O 

°o 

Ld 

. 

O 

PAST 

Fig.  1 

their  right  places;  that  is  the  job  before  me — to  put 
them  into  proper  location  in  my  frame  of  space  and 
time.  Among  them  I  can  immediately  recognise  and 
label  the  event  Here-Now,  viz.  that  which  is  happening 
in  this  room  at  this  moment.  The  other  events  are  at 
varying  degrees  of  remoteness  from  Here-Now,  and  it 


42  TIME 

is  obvious  to  me  that  the  remoteness  is  not  only  of 
different  degrees  but  of  different  kinds.  Some  events 
spread  away  towards  what  in  a  general  way  I  call  the 
Past;  I  can  contemplate  others  which  are  distant  in 
the  Future;  others  are  remote  in  another  kind  of  way 
towards  China  or  Peru,  or  in  general  terms  Elsewhere. 
In  this  picture  I  have  only  room  for  one  dimension  of 
Elsewhere;  another  dimension  sticks  out  at  right  angles 
to  the  paper;  and  you  must  imagine  the  third  dimension 
as  best  you  can. 

Now  we  must  pass  from  this  vague  scheme  of  location 
to  a  precise  scheme.  The  first  and  most  important  thing 
is  to  put  Myself  into  the  picture.  It  sounds  egotistical; 
but,  you  see,  it  is  my  frame  of  space  that  will  be  used, 
so  it  all  hangs  round  me.  Here  I  am — a  kind  of  four- 
dimensional  worm  (Fig.  2).  It  is  a  correct  portrait; 
I  have  considerable  extension  towards  the  Past  and 
presumably  towards  the  Future,  and  only  a  moderate 
extension  towards  Elsewhere.  The  "instantaneous  me", 
i.e.  myself  at  this  instant,  coincides  with  the  event  Here- 
Now.  Surveying  the  world  from  Here-Now,  I  can  see 
many  other  events  happening  now.  That  puts  it  into  my 
head  that  the  instant  of  which  I  am  conscious  here  must 
be  extended  to  include  them;  and  I  jump  to  the  con- 
clusion that  Now  is  not  confined  to  Here-Now.  I  there- 
fore draw  the  instant  Now,  running  as  a  clean  section 
across  the  world  of  events,  in  order  to  accommodate  all 
the  distant  events  which  are  happening  now.  I  select 
the  events  which  I  see  happening  now  and  place  them 
on  this  section,  which  I  call  a  moment  of  time  or  an 
"instantaneous  state  of  the  world".  I  locate  them  on 
Now  because  they  seem  to  be  Now. 

This  method  of  location  lasted  until  the  year  1667, 
when  it  was  found  impossible  to  make  it  work  consist- 


LOCATION  OF  EVENTS 


43 


ently.  It  was  then  discovered  by  the  astronomer  Roemer 
that  what  is  seen  now  cannot  be  placed  on  the  instant 
Now.  (In  ordinary  parlance — light  takes  time  to  travel.) 
That  was  really  a  blow  to  the  whole  system  of  world- 
wide instants,  which  were  specially  invented  to  accommo- 
date these  events.    We  had  been  mixing  up  two  distinct 


FUT 

URE 

Id 

Ld 

^    NOW 

c 

NHERE-NOW         /-.,              NOW    *^ 

Ld                "  ' "" 

^A 

A  ^                    '"  K..'        "                  Ld 

1                ^*'*' 

id-**- 

"*  Id 

</> 

<n 

_i 

-j 

Ld 

u. 

_J 
111 

(0 

> 
5 

id 

PAST 

Fig.  2^ 

events;  there  was  the  original  event  somewhere  out  in 
the  external  world  and  there  was  a  second  event,  viz. 
the  seeing  by  us  of  the  first  event.  The  second  event 
was  in  our  bodies  Here-Now;  the  first  event  was  neither 
Here  nor  Now.  The  experience  accordingly  gives  no 
indication  of  a  Now  which  is  not  Here;  and  we  might 


44  TIME 

well  have  abandoned  the  idea  that  we  have  intuitive 
recognition  of  a  Now  other  than  Here-Now,  which  was 
the  original  reason  for  postulating  world-wide  instants 
Now. 

However,  having  become  accustomed  to  world-wide 
instants,  physicists  were  not  ready  to  abandon  them. 
And,  indeed,  they  have  considerable  usefulness  pro- 
vided that  we  do  not  take  them  too  seriously.  They  were 
left  in  as  a  feature  of  the  picture,  and  two  Seen-Now 
lines  were  drawn,  sloping  backwards  from  the  Now  line, 
on  which  events  seen  now  could  be  consistently  placed. 
The  cotangent  of  the  angle  between  the  Seen-Now  lines 
and  the  Now  line  was  interpreted  as  the  velocity  of  light. 

Accordingly  when  I  see  an  event  in  a  distant  part  of 
the  universe,  e.g.  the  outbreak  of  a  new  star,  I  locate  it 
(quite  properly)  on  the  Seen-Now  line.  Then  I  make  a 
certain  calculation  from  the  measured  parallax  of  the 
star  and  draw  my  Now  line  to  pass,  say,  300  years  in 
front  of  the  event,  and  my  Now  line  of  300  years  ago 
to  pass  through  the  event.  By  this  method  I  trace  the 
course  of  my  Now  lines  or  world-wide  instants  among 
the  events,  and  obtain  a  frame  of  time-location  for 
external  events.  The  auxiliary  Seen-Now  lines,  having 
served  their  purpose,  are  rubbed  out  of  the  picture. 

That  is  how  /  locate  events;  how  about  youf  We 
must  first  put  You  into  the  picture  (Fig.  3).  We  shall 
suppose  that  you  are  on  another  star  moving  with 
different  velocity  but  passing  close  to  the  earth  at  the 
present  moment.  You  and  I  were  far  apart  in  the  past 
and  will  be  again  in  the  future,  but  we  are  both  Here- 
Now.  That  is  duly  shown  in  the  picture.  We  survey 
the  world  from  Here-Now,  and  of  course  we  both  see 
the  same  events  simultaneously.  We  may  receive  rather 
different    impressions    of    them;    our    different    motions 


LOCATION  OF  EVENTS 


45 


will  cause  different  Doppler  effects,  FitzGerald  con- 
tractions, etc.  There  may  be  slight  misunderstandings 
until  we  realise  that  what  you  describe  as  a  red  square 
is  what  I  would  describe  as  a  green  oblong,  and  so  on. 
But,  allowing  for  this  kind  of  difference  of  description, 


FUTURE 


id 

cc  MY  NQW 

Id   YoUR  N°^ 


Id 


HERE-NOW 


v0ornow. 

MY  NOW 


**-s£V 


2f? 


W 


Id 

cr 

Ld 

I 

U 

<0 

_J 

Id 


PAST 


Fig.  3 

it  will  soon  become  clear  that  we  are  looking  at  the  same 
events,  and  we  shall  agree  entirely  as  to  how  the  Seen- 
Now  lines  lie  with  respect  to  the  events.  Starting  from 
our  common  Seen-Now  lines,  you  have  next  to  make  the 
calculations  for  drawing  your  Now  line  among  the 
events,  and  you  trace  it  as  shown  in  Fig.  3. 


46  TIME 

How  is  it  that,  starting  from  the  same  Seen-Now 
lines,  you  do  not  reproduce  my  Now  line?  It  is  because 
a  certain  measured  quantity,  viz.  the  velocity  of  light, 
has  to  be  employed  in  the  calculations;  and  naturally 
you  trust  to  your  measures  of  it  as  I  trust  to  mine. 
Since  our  instruments  are  affected  by  different  Fitz- 
Gerald  contractions,  etc.,  there  is  plenty  of  room  for 
divergence.  Most  surprisingly  we  both  find  the  same 
velocity  of  light,  299,796  kilometres  per  second.  But 
this  apparent  agreement  is  really  a  disagreement;  be- 
cause you  take  this  to  be  the  velocity  relative  to  your 
planet  and  I  take  it  to  be  the  velocity  relative  to  mine.* 
Therefore  our  calculations  are  not  in  accord,  and  your 
Now  line  differs  from  mine. 

If  we  believe  our  world-wide  instants  or  Now  lines 
to  be  something  inherent  in  the  world  outside  us,  we 
shall  quarrel  frightfully.  To  my  mind  it  is  ridiculous 
that  you  should  take  events  on  the  right  of  the  picture 
which  have  not  -happened  yet  and  events  on  the  left 
which  are  already  past  and  call  the  combination  an 
instantaneous  condition  of  the  universe.  You  are 
equally  scornful  of  my  grouping.  We  can  never  agree. 
Certainly  it  looks  from  the  picture  as  though  my 
instants  were  more  natural  than  yours;  but  that  is 
because  /  drew  the  picture.  You,  of  course,  would 
redraw  it  with  your  Now  lines  at  right  angles  to  your- 
self. 


*  The  measured  velocity  of  light  is  the  average  to-and-fro  velocity. 
The  velocity  in  one  direction  singly  cannot  be  measured  until  after  the 
Now  lines  have  been  laid  down  and  therefore  cannot  be  used  in  laying 
down  the  Now  lines.  Thus  there  is  a  deadlock  in  drawing  the  Now  lines 
which  can  only  be  removed  by  an  arbitrary  assumption  or  convention. 
The  convention  actually  adopted  is  that  (relative  to  the  observer)  the 
velocities  of  light  in  the  two  opposite  directions  are  equal.  The  resulting 
Now  lines  must  therefore  be  regarded  as  equally  conventional. 


ABSOLUTE  PAST  AND  FUTURE  47 

But  we  need  not  quarrel  if  the  Now  lines  are  merely 
reference  lines  drawn  across  the  world  for  convenience 
in  locating  events — like  the  lines  of  latitude  and  longi- 
tude on  the  earth.  There  is  then  no  question  of  a  right 
way  and  a  wrong  way  of  drawing  the  lines;  we  draw 
them  as  best  suits  our  convenience.  World-wide  instants 
are  not  natural  cleavage  planes  of  time;  there  is  nothing 
equivalent  to  them  in  the  absolute  structure  of  the  world; 
they  are  imaginary  partitions  which  we  find  it  con- 
venient to  adopt. 

We  have  been  accustomed  to  regard  the  world — the 
enduring  world — as  stratified  into  a  succession  of  in- 
stantaneous states.  But  an  observer  on  another  star 
would  make  the  strata  run  in  a  different  direction  from 
ours.  We  shall  see  more  clearly  the  real  mechanism  of 
the  physical  world  if  we  can  rid  our  minds  of  this 
illusion  of  stratification.  The  world  that  then  stands 
revealed,  though  strangely  unfamiliar,  is  actually  much 
simpler.  There  is  a  difference  between  simplicity  and 
familiarity.  A  pig  may  be  most  familiar  to  us  in  the 
form  of  rashers,  but  the  unstratified  pig  is  a  simpler 
object  to  the  biologist  who  wishes  to  understand  how 
the  animal  functions. 

Absolute  Past  and  Future.  Let  us  now  try  to  attain  this 
absolute  view.  We  rub  out  all  the  Now  lines.  We  rub 
out  Yourself  and  Myself,  since  we  are  no  longer 
essential  to  the  world.  But  the  Seen-Now  lines  are  left. 
They  are  absolute,  since  all  observers  from  Here-Now 
agree  about  them.  The  flat  picture  is  a  section;  you 
must  imagine  it  rotated  (twice  rotated  in  fact,  since 
there  are  two  more  dimensions  outside  the  picture).  The 
Seen-Now  locus  is  thus  really  a  cone ;  or  by  taking  account 
of  the  prolongation  of  the  lines  into  the  future  a  double 


48  TIME 

cone  or  hour-glass  figure  (Fig.  4).  These  hour-glasses 
(drawn  through  each  point  of  the  world  considered  in 
turn  as  a  Here-Now)  embody  what  we  know  of  the  abso- 
lute structure  of  the  world  so  far  as  space  and  time  are 
concerned.  They  show  how  the  "grain"  of  the  world 
runs. 

Father  Time  has  been  pictured  as  an  old  man  with 
a  scythe  and  an  hour-glass.  We  no  longer  permit  him 
to  mow  instants  through  the  world  with  his  scythe;  but 
we  leave  him  his  hour-glass. 


ABSOLUTE       FUTURE 


ABSOLUTE  ^**^rv^^  ABSOLUTE 

ELSEWHERE  ^^^itMtrnvw  ELSEWHERE 


ABSOLUTE       PAST 


«*g£^~-  —  -^W 


Fig.  4 

Since  the  hour-glass  is  absolute  its  two  cones  provide 
respectively  an  Absolute  Future  and  an  Absolute  Past 
for  the  event  Here-Now.  They  are  separated  by  a 
wedge-shaped  neutral  zone  which  (absolutely)  is  neither 
past  nor  future.  The  common  impression  that  relativity 
turns  past  and  future  altogether  topsy-turvy  is  quite 
false.  But,  unlike  the  relative  past  and  future,  the 
absolute  past  and  future  are  not  separated  by  an  in- 
finitely   narrow    present.      It    suggests    itself    that    the 


ABSOLUTE  PAST  AND  FUTURE  49 

neutral  wedge  might  be  called  the  Absolute  Present ;  but  I 
do  not  think  that  is  a  good  nomenclature.  It  is  much 
better  described  as  Absolute  Elsewhere.  We  have 
abolished  the  Now  lines,  and  in  the  absolute  world  the 
present  (Now)  is  restricted  to  Here-Now. 

Perhaps  I  may  illustrate  the  peculiar  conditions 
arising  from  the  wedge-shaped  neutral  zone  by  a  rather 
hypothetical  example.  Suppose  that  you  are  in  love  with 
a  lady  on  Neptune  and  that  she  returns  the  sentiment. 
It  will  be  some  consolation  for  the  melancholy  separation 
if  you  can  say  to  yourself  at  some — possibly  pre- 
arranged— moment,  "She  is  thinking  of  me  now". 
Unfortunately  a  difficulty  has  arisen  because  we  have 
had  to  abolish  Now.  There  is  no  absolute  Now,  but 
only  the  various  relative  Nows  differing  according  to 
the  reckoning  of  different  observers  and  covering  the 
whole  neutral  wedge  which  at  the  distance  of  Neptune 
is  about  eight  hours  thick.  She  will  have  to  think  of 
you  continuously  for  eight  hours  on  end  in  order  to 
circumvent  the  ambiguity  of  "Now". 

At  the  greatest  possible  separation  on  the  earth  the 
thickness  of  the  neutral  wedge  is  no  more  than  a  tenth 
of  a  second;  so  that  terrestrial  synchronism  is  not 
seriously  interfered  with.  This  suggests  a  qualification 
of  our  previous  conclusion  that  the  absolute  present  is 
confined  to  Here-Now.  It  is  true  as  regards  instan- 
taneous events  (point-events).  But  in  practice  the 
events  we  notice  are  of  more  than  infinitesimal  duration. 
If  the  duration  is  sufficient  to  cover  the  width  of  the 
neutral  zone,  then  the  event  taken  as  a  whole  may  fairly 
be  considered  to  be  Now  absolutely.  From  this  point 
of  view  the  "nowness"  of  an  event  is  like  a  shadow  cast 
by  it  into  space,  and  the  longer  the  event  the  farther 
will  the  umbra  of  the  shadow  extend. 


50  TIME 

As  the  speed  of  matter  approaches  the  speed  of  light 
its  mass  increases  to  infinity,  and  therefore  it  is  impos- 
sible to  make  matter  travel  faster  than  light.  This 
conclusion  is  deduced  from  the  classical  laws  of  physics, 
and  the  increase  of  mass  has  been  verified  by  experiment 
up  to  very  high  velocities.  In  the  absolute  world  this 
means  that  a  particle  of  matter  can  only  proceed  from 
Here-Now  into  the  absolute  future — which,  you  will 
agree,  is  a  reasonable  and  proper  restriction.  It  cannot 
travel  into  the  neutral  zone;  the  limiting  cone  is  the 
track  of  light  or  of  anything  moving  with  the  speed  of 
light.  We  ourselves  are  attached  to  material  bodies,  and 
therefore  we  can  only  go  on  into  the  absolute  future. 

Events  in  the  absolute  future  are  not  absolutely 
Elsewhere.  It  would  be  possible  for  an  observer  to 
travel  from  Here-Now  to  the  event  in  question  in  time 
to  experience  it,  since  the  required  velocity  is  less  than 
that  of  light;  relative  to  the  frame  of  such  an  observer 
the  event  would  be  Here.  No  observer  can  reach  an 
event  in  the  neutral  zone,  since  the  required  speed  is  too 
great.  The  event  is  not  Here  for  any  observer  (from 
Here-Now) ;  therefore  it  is  absolutely  Elsewhere. 

The  Absolute  Distinction  of  Space  and  Time.  By  divid- 
ing the  world  into  Absolute  Past  and  Future  on  the  one 
hand  and  Absolute  Elsewhere  on  the  other  hand,  our 
hour-glasses  have  restored  a  fundamental  differentiation 
between  time  and  space.  It  is  not  a  distinction  between 
time  and  space  as  they  appear  in  a  space-time  frame,  but 
a  distinction  between  temporal  and  spatial  relations. 
Events  can  stand  to  us  in  a  temporal  relation  (absolutely 
past  or  future)  or  a  spatial  relation  (absolutely  else- 
where), but  not  in  both.  The  temporal  relations  radiate 
into  the  past  and  future  cones  and  the  spatial  relations 


DISTINCTION  OF  SPACE  AND  TIME  51 

into  the  neutral  wedge;  they  are  kept  absolutely  sepa- 
rated by  the  Seen-Now  lines  which  we  have  identified  with 
the  grain  of  absolute  structure  in  the  world.  We  have 
recovered  the  distinction  which  the  Astronomer  Royal 
confused  when  he  associated  time  with  the  merely  arti- 
ficial Now  lines. 

I  would  direct  your  attention  to  an  important  differ- 
ence in  our  apprehension  of  time-extension  and  space- 
extension.  As  already  explained  our  course  through  the 
world  is  into  the  absolute  future,  i.e.  along  a  sequence 
of  time-relations.  We  can  never  have  a  similar  experi- 
ence of  a  sequence  of  space-relations  because  that 
would  involve  travelling  with  velocity  greater  than  light. 
Thus  we  have  immediate  experience  of  the  time-relation 
but  not  of  the  space-relation.  Our  knowledge  of  space- 
relations  is  indirect,  like  nearly  all  our  knowledge  of  the 
external  world — a  matter  of  inference  and  interpretation 
of  the  impressions  which  reach  us  through  our  sense- 
organs.  We  have  similar  indirect  knowledge  of  the 
time-relations  existing  between  the  events  in  the  world 
outside  us;  but  in  addition  we  have  direct  experience 
of  the  time-relations  that  we  ourselves  are  traversing — 
a  knowledge  of  time  not  coming  through  external  sense- 
organs,  but  taking  a  short  cut  into  our  consciousness. 
When  I  close  my  eyes  and  retreat  into  my  inner  mind, 
I  feel  myself  enduring,  I  do  not  feel  myself  extensive.  It 
is  this  feeling  of  time  as  affecting  ourselves  and  not 
merely  as  existing  in  the  relations  of  external  events 
which  is  so  peculiarly  characteristic  of  it;  space  on  the 
other  hand  is  always  appreciated  as  something  external. 

That  is  why  time  seems  to  us  so  much  more  mysteri- 
ous than  space.  We  know  nothing  about  the  intrinsic 
nature  of  space,  and  so  it  is  quite  easy  to  conceive  it 
satisfactorily.     We  have  intimate  acquaintance  with  the 


52  TIME 

nature  of  time  and  so  it  baffles  our  comprehension.  It 
is  the  same  paradox  which  makes  us  believe  we  under- 
stand the  nature  of  an  ordinary  table  whereas  the  nature 
of  human  personality  is  altogether  mysterious.  We 
never  have  that  intimate  contact  with  space  and  tables 
which  would  make  us  realise  how  mysterious  they  are; 
we  have  direct  knowledge  of  time  and  of  the  human 
spirit  which  makes  us  reject  as  inadequate  that  merely 
symbolic  conception  of  the  world  which  is  so  often  mis- 
taken for  an  insight  into  its  nature. 

The  Four-Dimensional  World.  I  do  not  know  whether 
you  have  been  keenly  alive  to  the  fact  that  for  some  time 
now  we  have  been  immersed  in  a  four-dimensional 
world.  The  fourth  dimension  required  no  introduction; 
as  soon  as  we  began  to  consider  events  it  was  there. 
Events  obviously  have  a  fourfold  order  which  we  can 
dissect  into  right  or  left,  behind  or  in  front,  above  or 
below,  sooner  or  later — or  into  many  alternative  sets  of 
fourfold  specification.  The  fourth  dimension  is  not  a 
difficult  conception.  It  is  not  difficult  to.  conceive  of 
events  as  ordered  in  four  dimensions;  it  is  impossible  to 
conceive  them  otherwise.  The  trouble  begins  when  we 
continue  farther  along  this  line  of  thought,  because  by 
long  custom  we  have  divided  the  world  of  events  into 
three-dimensional  sections  or  instants,  and  regarded  the 
piling  of  the  instants  as  something  distinct  from  a 
dimension.  That  gives  us  the  usual  conception  of  a 
three-dimensional  world  floating  in  the  stream  of  time. 
This  pampering  of  a  particular  dimension  is  not  entirely 
without  foundation;  it  is  our  crude  appreciation  of  the 
absolute  separation  of  space-relations  and  time-relations 
by  the  hour-glass  figures.  But  the  crude  discrimination 
has  to  be  replaced  by  a  more  accurate  discrimination. 


THE  FOUR-DIMENSIONAL  WORLD  53 

The  supposed  planes  of  structure  represented  bj 
Now  lines  separated  one  dimension  from  the  other 
three;  but  the  cones  of  structure  given  by  the  hour- 
glass figures  keep  the  four  dimensions  firmly  pinned 
together.* 

We  are  accustomed  to  think  of  a  man  apart  from  his 
duration.  When  I  portrayed  "Myself"  in  Fig.  2,  you 
were  for  the  moment  surprised  that  I  should  include 
my  boyhood  and  old  age.  But  to  think  of  a  man  without 
his  duration  is  just  as  abstract  as  to  think  of  a  man 
without  his  inside.  Abstractions  are  useful,  and  a  man 
without  his  inside  (that  is  to  say,  a  surface)  is  a  well- 
known  geometrical  conception.  But  we  ought  to  realise 
what  is  an  abstraction  and  what  is  not.  The  "four- 
dimensional  worms"  introduced  in  this  chapter  seem  to 
many  people  terribly  abstract.  Not  at  all;  they  are  un- 
familiar conceptions  but  not  abstract  conceptions.  It  is 
the  section  of  the  worm  (the  man  Now)  which  is  an 
abstraction.  And  as  sections  may  be  taken  in  somewhat 
different  directions,  the  abstraction  is  made  differently 
by  different  observers  who  accordingly  attribute  different 
FitzGerald  contractions  to  it.  The  non-abstract  man 
enduring  through  time  is  the  common  source  from  which 
the  different  abstractions  are  made. 

The  appearance  of  a  four-dimensional  world  in  this 
subject  is  due  to  Minkowski.  Einstein  showed  the  rela- 
tivity of  the  familiar  quantities  of  physics;  Minkowski 
showed  how  to  recover  the  absolute  by  going  back  to 
their  four-dimensional  origin  and  searching  more  deeply. 

*  In  Fig.  4  the  scale  is  such  that  a  second  of  time  corresponds  to 
70,000  miles  of  space.  If  we  take  a  more  ordinary  scale  of  experience, 
say  a  second  to  a  yard,  the  Seen-Now  lines  become  almost  horizontal; 
and  it  will  easily  be  understood  why  the  cones  which  pin  the  four 
dimensions  together  have  generally  been  mistaken  for  sections  separating 
them. 


54  TIME 

The  Velocity  of  Light.  A  feature  of  the  relativity 
theory  which  seems  to  have  aroused  special  interest 
among  philosophers  is  the  absoluteness  of  the  velocity  of 
light.  In  general  velocity  is  relative.  If  I  speak  of  a 
velocity  of  40  kilometres  a  second  I  must  add  "relative 
to  the  earth",  "relative  to  Arcturus",  or  whatever  refer- 
ence body  I  have  in  mind.  No  one  will  understand  any- 
thing from  my  statement  unless  this  is  added  or  implied. 
But  it  is  a  curious  fact  that  if  I  speak  of  a  velocity 
of  299,796  kilometres  a  second  it  is  unnecessary  to 
add  the  explanatory  phrase.  Relative  to  what?  Rela- 
tive to  any  and  every  star  or  particle  of  matter  in  the 
universe. 

It  is  no  use  trying  to  overtake  a  flash  of  light; 
however  fast  you  go  it  is  always  travelling  away  from 
you  at  186,000  miles  a  second.  Now  from  one  point 
of  view  this  is  a  rather  unworthy  deception  that  Nature 
has  practised  upon  us.  Let  us  take  our  favourite  observer 
who  travels  at  161,000  miles  a  second  and  send  him  in 
pursuit  of  the  flash  of  light.  It  is  going  25,000  miles 
a  second  faster  than  he  is;  but  that  is  not  what  he  will 
report.  Owing  to  the  contraction  of  his  standard  scale 
his  miles  are  only  half-miles;  owing  to  the  slowing  down 
of  his  clocks  his  seconds  are  double-seconds.  His 
measurements  would  therefore  make  the  speed  100,000 
miles  a  second  (really  half-miles  per  double-second). 
He  makes  a  further  mistake  in  synchronising  the  clocks 
with  which  he  records  the  velocity.  (You  will  remember 
that  he  uses  a  different  Now  line  from  ours.).  This 
brings  the  speed  up  to  186,000  miles  a  second.  From 
his  own  point  of  view  the  traveller  is  lagging  hopelessly 
behind  the  light;  he  does  not  realise  what  a  close  race 
he  is  making  of  it,  because  his  measuring  appliances 
have  been  upset.     You  will  note  that  the  evasiveness  of 


THE  VELOCITY  OF  LIGHT  55 

the  light-flash  is  not  in  the  least  analogous  to  the 
evasiveness  of  the  rainbow. 

But  although  this  explanation  may  help  to  reconcile 
us  to  what  at  first  seems  a  blank  impossibility,  it  is  not 
really  the  most  penetrating.  You  will  remember  that 
a  Seen-Now  line,  or  track  of  a  flash  of  light,  represents 
the  grain  of  the  world-structure.  Thus  the  peculiarity 
of  a  velocity  of  299,796  kilometres  a  second  is  that  it 
coincides  with  the  grain  of  the  world.  The  four- 
dimensional  worms  representing  material  bodies  must 
necessarily  run  across  the  grain  into  the  future  cone,  and 
we  have  to  introduce  some  kind  of  reference  frame  to 
describe  their  course.  But  the  flash  of  light  is  exactly 
along  the  grain,  and  there  is  no  need  of  any  artificial 
system  of  partitions  to  describe  this  fact. 

The  number  299,796  (kilometres  per  second)  is, 
so  to  speak,  a  code-number  for  the  grain  of  the  wood. 
Other  code-numbers  correspond  to  the  various  worm- 
holes  which  may  casually  cross  the  grain.  We  have 
different  codes  corresponding  to  different  frames  of 
space  and  time;  the  code-number  of  the  grain  of  the 
wood  is  the  only  one  which  is  the  same  in  all  codes. 
This  is  no  accident;  but  I  do  not  know  that  any  deep 
inference  is  to  be  drawn  from  it,  other  than  that  our 
measure-codes  have  been  planned  rationally  so  as  to  turn 
on  the  essential  and  not  on  the  casual  features  of  world- 
structure. 

The  speed  of  299,796  kilometres  per  second  which 
occupies  a  unique  position  in  every  measure-system  is 
commonly  referred  to  as  the  speed  of  light.  But  it  is 
much  more  than  that;  it  is  the  speed  at  which  the  mass 
of  matter  becomes  infinite,  lengths  contract  to  zero, 
clocks  stand  still.  Therefore  it  crops  up  in  all  kinds  of 
problems  whether  light  is  concerned  or  not. 


56  TIME 

The  scientist's  interest  in  the  absoluteness  of  this 
velocity  is  very  great;  the  philosopher's  interest  has 
been,  I  think,  largely  a  mistaken  interest.  In  asserting 
its  absoluteness  scientists  mean  that  they  have  assigned 
the  same  number  to  it  in  every  measure-system;  but 
that  is  a  private  arrangement  of  their  own — an  un- 
witting compliment  to  its  universal  importance.*  Turn- 
ing from  the  measure-numbers  to  the  thing  described 
by  them,  the  "grain"  is  certainly  an  absolute  feature 
of  the  wood,  but  so  also  are  the  "worm-holes" 
(material  particles).  The  difference  is  that  the  grain  is 
essential  and  universal,  the  worm-holes  casual.  Science 
and  philosophy  have  often  been  at  cross-purposes  in 
discussing  the  Absolute — a  misunderstanding  which  is 
I  am  afraid  chiefly  the  fault  of  the  scientists.  In  science 
we  are  chiefly  concerned  with  the  absoluteness  or  relativity 
of  the  descriptive  terms  we  employ;  but  when  the  term 
absolute  is  used  with  reference  to  that  which  is  being 
described  it  has  generally  the  loose  meaning  of  "uni- 
versal" as  opposed  to  "casual". 

Another  point  on  which  there  has  sometimes  been  a 
misunderstanding  is  the  existence  of  a  superior  limit  to 
velocity.  It  is  not  permissible  to  say  that  no  velocity  can 
exceed  299,796  kilometres  per  second.  For  example, 
imagine  a  search-light  capable  of  sending  an  accurately 
parallel  beam  as  far  as  Neptune.  If  the  search-light  is 
made  to  revolve  once  a  minute,  Neptune's  end  of  the 
beam  will  move  round  a  circle  with  velocity  far  greater 
than  the  above  limit.  This  is  an  example  of  our  habit 
of  creating  velocities  by  a  mental  association  of  states 

*  In  the  general  relativity  theory  (chapter  vi)  measure-systems  are 
employed  in  which  the  velocity  of  light  is  no  longer  assigned  the  same 
constant  value,  but  it  continues  to  correspond  to  the  grain  of  absolute 
world-structure. 


THE  VELOCITY  OF  LIGHT  57 

which  are  not  themselves  in  direct  causal  connection. 
The  assertion  made  by  the  relativity  theory  is  more 
restricted,  viz. — 

Neither  matter,  nor  energy,  nor  anything  capable  of 
being  used  as  a  signal  can  travel  faster  than  299,796 
kilometres  per  second,  provided  that  the  velocity  is 
referred  to  one  of  the  frames  of  space  and  time  con- 
sidered in  this  chapter.* 

The  velocity  of  light  in  matter  can  under  certain 
circumstances  (in  the  phenomenon  of  anomalous  dis- 
persion) exceed  this  value.  But  the  higher  velocity  is 
only  attained  after  the  light  has  been  passing  through 
the  matter  for  some  moments  so  as  to  set  the  molecules 
in  sympathetic  vibration.  An  unheralded  light-flash 
travels  more  slowly.  The  speed,  exceeding  299,796 
kilometres  a  second,  is,  so  to  speak,  achieved 
by  prearrangement,  and  has  no  application  in  sig- 
nalling. 

We  are  bound  to  insist  on  this  limitation  of  the  speed 
of  signalling.  It  has  the  effect  that  it  is  only  possible  to 
signal  into  the  Absolute  Future.  The  consequences  of 
being  able  to  transmit  messages  concerning  events 
Here-Now  into  the  neutral  wedge  are  too  bizarre  to 
contemplate.  Either  the  part  of  the  neutral  wedge  that 
can  be  reached  by  the  signals  must  be  restricted  in  a 
way  which  violates  the  principle  of  relativity;  or  it  will 
be  possible  to  arrange  for  a  confederate  to  receive  the 
messages  which  we  shall  send  him  to-morrow,  and  to 
retransmit  them  to  us  so  that  we  receive  them  to-dav^' 
The    limit    to    the    velocity   of    signals    is    our    bulwark 

*  Some  proviso  of  this  kind  is  clearly  necessary.  We  often  employ 
for  special  purposes  a  frame  of  reference  rotating  with  the  earth;  in  this 
frame  the  stars  describe  circles  once  a  day,  and  are  therefore  ascribed 
enormous  velocities. 


58  TIME 

against  that  topsy-turvydom  of  past  and  future,  of  which 
Einstein's  theory  is  sometimes  wrongfully  accused. 

Expressed  in  the  conventional  way  this  limitation  of 
the  speed  of  signalling  to  299,796  kilometres  a 
second  seems  a  rather  arbitrary  decree  of  Nature.  We 
almost  feel  it  as  a  challenge  to  find  something  that  goes 
faster.  But  if  we  state  it  in  the  absolute  form  that 
signalling  is  only  possible  along  a  track  of  temporal 
relation  and  not  along  a  track  of  spatial  relation  the 
restriction  seems  rational.  To  violate  it  we  have  not 
merely  to  find  something  which  goes  just  1  kilometre 
per  second  better,  but  something  which  overleaps  that 
distinction  of  time  and  space — which,  we  are  all  con- 
vinced, ought  to  be  maintained  in  any  sensible  theory. 

Practical  Applications.  In  these  lectures  I  am  concerned 
more  with  the  ideas  of  the  new  theories  than  with  their 
practical  importance  for  the  advancement  of  science. 
But  the  drawback  of  dwelling  solely  on  the  underlying 
conceptions  is  that  it  is  likely  to  give  the  impression  that 
the  new  physics  is  very  much  uup  in  the  air".  That  is 
by  no  means  true,  and  the  relativity  theory  is  used  in 
a  businesslike  way  in  the  practical  problems  to  which 
it  applies.  I  can  only  consider  here  quite  elementary 
problems  which  scarcely  do  justice  to  the  power  of  the 
new  theory  in  advanced  scientific  research.  Two 
examples  must  suffice. 

1.  It  has  often  been  suggested  that  the  stars  will  be 
retarded  by  the  back-pressure  of  their  own  radiation. 
The  idea  is  that  since  the  star  is  moving  forward  the 
emitted  radiation  is  rather  heaped  up  in  front  of  it  and 
thinned  out  behind.  Since  radiation  exerts  pressure  the 
pressure  will  be  stronger  on  the  front  surface  than  on 
the  rear,    Therefore  there  is  a  force  retarding  the  star 


PRACTICAL  APPLICATIONS  59 

tending  to  bring  it  gradually  to  rest.  The  effect  might 
be  of  great  importance  in  the  study  of  stellar  motions; 
it  would  mean  that  on  the  average  old  stars  must  have 
lower  speeds  than  young  stars — a  conclusion  which,  as 
it  happens,  is  contrary  to  observation. 

But  according  to  the  theory  of  relativity  "coming  to 
rest"  has  no  meaning.  A  decrease  of  velocity  relative 
to  one  frame  is  an  increase  relative  to  another  frame. 
There  is  no  absolute  velocity  and  no  absolute  rest  for 
the  star  to  come  to.  The  suggestion  may  therefore  be 
at  once  dismissed  as  fallacious. 

2.  The  B  particles  shot  out  by  radioactive  substances 
are  electrons  travelling  at  speeds  not  much  below 
the  speed  of  light.  Experiment  shows  that  the  mass 
of  one  of  these  high-speed  electrons  is  considerably 
greater  than  the  mass  of  an  electron  at  rest.  The  theory 
of  relativity  predicts  this  increase  and  provides  the 
formula  for  the  dependence  of  mass  on  velocity.  The 
increase  arises  solely  from  the  fact  that  mass  is  a  relative 
quantity  depending  by  definition  on  the  relative  quan- 
tities length  and  time. 

Let  us  look  at  a  3  particle  from  its  own  point  of  view. 
It  is  an  ordinary  electron  in  no  wise  different  from  any 
other.  But  it  is  travelling  with  unusually  high  speed? 
"No",  says  the  electron,  "That  is  your  point  of  view. 
I  contemplate  with  amazement  your  extraordinary 
speed  of  100,000  miles  a  second  with  which  you  are 
shooting  past  me.  I  wonder  what  it  feels  like  to  move 
so  quickly.  However,  it  is  no  business  of  mine."  So 
the  p  particle,  smugly  thinking  itself  at  rest,  pays  no 
attention  to  our  goings  on,  and  arranges  itself  with  the 
usual  mass,  radius  and  charge.  It  has  just  the  standard 
mass  of  an  electron,  9.10"28  grams.  But  mass  and 
radius  are  relative  quantities,  and  in  this  case  the  frame 


60  TIME 

to  which  they  are  referred  is  evidently  the  frame  appro- 
priate to  an  electron  engaged  in  self-contemplation,  viz. 
the  frame  in  which  it  is  at  rest  But  when  we  talk  about 
mass  we  refer  it  to  the  frame  in  which  we  are  at  rest. 
By  the  geometry  of  the  four-dimensional  world  we  can 
calculate  the  formulae  for  the  change  of  reckoning  of 
mass  in  two  different  frames,  which  is  consequential  on 
the  change  of  reckoning  of  length  and  time;  we  find 
in  fact  that  the  mass  is  increased  in  the  same  ratio  as  the 
length  is  diminished  (FitzGerald  factor).  The  increase 
of  mass  that  we  observe  arises  from  the  change  of 
reckoning  between  the  electron's  own  frame  and  our 
frame. 

All  electrons  are  alike  from  their  own  point  of  view. 
The  apparent  differences  arise  in  fitting  them  into  our 
own  frame  of  reference  which  is  irrelevant  to  their 
structure.  Our  reckoning  of  their  mass  is  higher  than 
their  own  reckoning,  and  increases  with  the  difference 
between  our  respective  frames,  i.e.  with  the  relative 
velocity  between  us. 

We  do  not  bring  forward  these  results  to  demonstrate 
or  confirm  the  truth  of  the  theory,  but  to  show  the  use 
of  the  theory.  They  can  both  be  deduced  from  the 
classical  electromagnetic  theory  of  Maxwell  coupled  (in 
the  second  problem)  with  certain  plausible  assumptions 
as  to  the  conditions  holding  at  the  surface  of  an  electron. 
But  to  realise  the  advantage  of  the  new  theory  we  must 
consider  not  what  could  have  been  but  what  was  deduced 
from  the  classical  theory.  The  historical  fact  is  that  the 
conclusions  of  the  classical  theory  as  to  the  first  prob- 
lem were  wrong;  an  important  compensating  factor 
escaped  notice.  Its  conclusions  as  to  the  second  problem 
were  (after  some  false  starts)  entirely  correct  numer- 
ically.   But  since  the  result  was  deduced  from  the  electro- 


SUMMARY  61 

magnetic  equations  of  the  electron  it  was  thought  that 
it  depended  on  the  fact  that  an  electron  is  an  electrical 
structure;  and  the  agreement  with  observation  was 
believed  to  confirm  the  hypothesis  that  an  electron  is 
pure  electricity  and  nothing  else.  Our  treatment  above 
makes  no  reference  to  any  electrical  properties  of  the 
electron,  the  phenomenon  having  been  found  to  arise 
solely  from  the  relativity  of  mass.  Hence,  although 
there  may  be  other  good  reasons  for  believing  that  an 
electron  consists  solely  of  negative  electricity,  the  in- 
crease of  mass  with  velocity  is  no  evidence  one  way  or 
the  other. 

In  this  chapter  the  idea  of  a  multiplicity  of  frames  of 
space  has  been  extended  to  a  multiplicity  of  frames  of 
space  and  time.     The  system  of  location  in  space,  called 
a  frame  of  space,  is  only  a  part  of  a  fuller  system  of 
location  of  events  in  space  and  time.     Nature  provides 
no  indication  that  one  of  these  frames  is  to  be  preferred 
to  the  others.     The  particular  frame  in  which  we  are 
relatively   at   rest   has    a   symmetry   with   respect   to   us 
which  other  frames  do  not  possess,  and  for  this  reason 
we  have  drifted  into  the  common  assumption  that  it  is 
the  only  reasonable  and  proper  frame;  but  this  egocen- 
tric outlook  should  now  be  abandoned,   and  all   frames 
treated   as   on   the   same    footing.      By  considering   time 
and   space    together   we  have  been   able   to   understand 
how  the  multiplicity  of  frames  arises.     They  correspond 
to  different  directions  of  section  of  the  four-dimensional 
world    of    events,    the    sections    being    the    "world-wide 
instants".      Simultaneity    (Now)   is   seen  to  be   relative. 
The   denial   of   absolute   simultaneity  is   intimately  con- 
nected with  the  denial  of  absolute  velocity;  knowledge 
of    absolute    velocity    would    enable    us    to    assert    that 


62  TIME 

certain  events  in  the  past  or  future  occur  Here  but  not 
Now;  knowledge  of  absolute  simultaneity  would  tell  us 
that  certain  events  occur  Now  but  not  Here.  Removing 
these  artificial  sections,  we  have  had  a  glimpse  of  the 
absolute  world-structure  with  its  grain  diverging  and 
interlacing  after  the  plan  of  the  hour-glass  figures.  By 
reference  to  this  structure  we  discern  an  absolute  dis- 
tinction between  space-like  and  time-like  separation  of 
events — a  distinction  which  justifies  and  explains  our 
instinctive  feeling  that  space  and  time  are  fundamentally 
different.  Many  of  the  important  applications  of  the 
new  conceptions  to  the  practical  problems  of  physics 
are  too  technical  to  be  considered  in  this  book;  one  of 
the  simpler  applications  is  to  determine  the  changes  of 
the  physical  properties  of  objects  due  to  rapid  motion. 
Since  the  motion  can  equally  well  be  described  as  a 
motion  of  ourselves  relative  to  the  object  or  of  the 
object  relative  to  ourselves,  it  cannot  influence  the  abso- 
lute behaviour  of  the  object.  The  apparent  changes  in 
the  length,  mass,  electric  and  magnetic  fields,  period  of 
vibration,  etc.,  are  merely  a  change  of  reckoning  intro- 
duced in  passing  from  the  frame  in  which  the  object  is 
at  rest  to  the  frame  in  which  the  observer  is  at  rest. 
Formulae  for  calculating  the  change  of  reckoning  of 
any  of  these  quantities  are  easily  deduced  now  that  the 
geometrical  relation  of  the  frames  has  been  ascertained. 


Chapter  IV 

THE    RUNNING-DOWN    OF    THE    UNIVERSE 

Shuffling.  The  modern  outlook  on  the  physical  world  is 
not  composed  exclusively  of  conceptions  which  have 
arisen  in  the  last  twenty-five  years;  and  we  have  now 
to  deal  with  a  group  of  ideas  dating  far  back  in  the  last 
century  which  have  not  essentially  altered  since  the 
time  of  Boltzmann.  These  ideas  display  great  activity 
and  development  at  the  present  time.  The  subject  is 
relevant  at  this  stage  because  it  has  a  bearing  on  the 
deeper  aspects  of  the  problem  of  Time;  but  it  is  so 
fundamental  in  physical  theory  that  we  should  be  bound 
to  deal  with  it  sooner  or  later  in  any  comprehensive 
survey. 

If  you  take  a  pack  of  cards  as  it  comes  from  the 
maker  and  shuffle  it  for  a  few  minutes,  all  trace  of 
the  original  systematic  order  disappears.  The  order  wiil 
never  come  back  however  long  you  shuffle.  Something 
has  been  done  which  cannot  be  undone,  namely,  the  intro- 
duction of  a  random  element  in  place  of  arrangement. 

Illustrations  may  be  useful  even  when  imperfect,  and 
therefore  I  have  slurred  over  two  points,  which  affect 
the  illustration  rather  than  the  application  which  we  are 
about  to  make.  It  was  scarcely  true  to  say  that  the 
shuffling  cannot  be  undone.  You  can  sort  out  the  cards 
into  their  original  order  if  you  like.  But  in  considering 
the  shuffling  which  occurs  in  the  physical  world  we  are 
not  troubled  by  a  deus  ex  machina  like  you.  I  am  not 
prepared  to  say  how  far  the  human  mind  is  bound  by  the 
conclusions  we  shall  reach.  So  I  exclude  you — at  least 
I  exclude  that  activity  of  your  mind  which  you  employ 

63 


64     THE  RUNNING-DOWN  OF  THE  UNIVERSE 

in  sorting  the  cards.  I  allow  you  to  shuffle  them  because 
you  can  do  that  absent-mindedly. 

Secondly,  it  is  not  quite  true  that  the  original  order 
never  comes  back.  There  is  a  ghost  of  a  chance  that 
some  day  a  thoroughly  shuffled  pack  will  be  found  to 
have  come  back  to  the  original  order.  That  is  because 
of  the  comparatively  small  number  of  cards  in  the  pack. 
In  our  applications  the  units  are  so  numerous  that  this 
kind  of  contingency  can  be  disregarded. 

We  shall  put  forward  the  contention  that — 

Whenever  anything  happens  which  cannot  be  undone, 
it  is  always  reducible  to  the  introduction  of  a  random 
element  analogous  to  that  introduced  by  shuffling. 

Shuffling  is  the   only  thing  which   Nature   cannot  undo. 
When  Humpty  Dumpty  had  a  great   fall — 

All  the  king's  horses  and  all  the  king's  men 
Cannot  put  Humpty  Dumpty  together  again. 

Something  had  happened  which  could  not  be  undone. 
The  fall  could  have  been  undone.  It  is  not  necessary  to 
invoke  the  king's  horses  and  the  king's  men;  if  there 
had  been  a  perfectly  elastic  mat  underneath,  that  would 
have  sufficed.  At  the  end  of  his  fall  Humpty  Dumpty 
had  kinetic  energy  which,  properly  directed,  was  just 
sufficient  to  bounce  him  back  on  to  the  wall  again.  But, 
the  elastic  mat  being  absent,  an  irrevocable  event  hap- 
pened at  the  end  of  the  fall — namely,  the  introduction 
of  a  random  element  into  Humpty  Dumpty. 

But  why  should  we  suppose  that  shuffling  is  the  only 
process  that  cannot  be  undone? 

The  Moving  Finger  writes;  and,  having  writ, 
Moves  on:  nor  all  thy  Piety  and  Wit 
Can  lure  it  back  to  cancel  half  a  Line. 


SHUFFLING  65 

When  there  is  no  shuffling,  is  the  Moving  Finger  stayed? 
The  answer  of  physics  is  unhesitatingly  Yes.  To  judge 
of  this  we  must  examine  those  operations  of  Nature  in 
which  no  increase  of  the  random  element  can  possibly 
occur.  These  fall  into  two  groups.  Firstly,  we  can 
study  those  laws  of  Nature  which  control  the  behaviour 
of  a  single  unit.  Clearly  no  shuffling  can  occur  in  these 
problems;  you  cannot  take  the  King  of  Spades  away 
from  the  pack  and  shuffle  him.  Secondly,  we  can  study 
the  processes  of  Nature  in  a  crowd  which  is  already  so 
completely  shuffled  that  there  is  no  room  for  any  further 
increase  of  the  random  element.  If  our  contention  is 
right,  everything  that  occurs  in  these  conditions  is 
capable  of  being  undone.  We  shall  consider  the  first 
condition  immediately;  the  second  must  be  deferred 
until  p.  78. 

Any  change  occurring  to  a  body  which  can  be  treated 
as  a  single  unit  can  be  undone.  The  laws  of  Nature 
admit  of  the  undoing  as  easily  as  of  the  doing.  The 
earth  describing  its  orbit  is  controlled  by  laws  of  motion 
and  of  gravitation;  these  admit  of  the  earth's  actual  mo- 
tion, but  they  also  admit  of  the  precisely  opposite 
motion.  In  the  same  field  of  force  the  earth  could  retrace 
its  steps;  it  merely  depends  on  how  it  was  started  off.  It 
may  be  objected  that  we  have  no  right  to  dismiss  the 
starting-off  as  an  inessential  part  of  the  problem;  it  may 
be  as  much  a  part  of  the  coherent  scheme  of  Nature  as 
the  laws  controlling  the  subsequent  motion.  Indeed,  as- 
tronomers have  theories  explaining  why  the  eight  planets 
all  started  to  move  the  same  way  round  the  sun.  But 
that  is  a  problem  of  eight  planets,  not  of  a  single 
individual — a  problem  of  the  pack,  not  of  the  isolated 
card.  So  long  as  the  earth's  motion  is  treated  as  an 
isolated  problem,  no  one  would  dream  of  putting  into 


66     THE  RUNNING-DOWN  OF  THE  UNIVERSE 

the  laws  of  Nature  a  clause  requiring  that  it  must  go 
this  way  round  and  not  the  opposite. 

There  is  a  similar  reversibility  of  motion  in  fields  of 
electric  and  magnetic  force.  Another  illustration  can  be 
given  from  atomic  physics.  The  quantum  laws  admit 
of  the  emission  of  certain  kinds  and  quantities  of  light 
from  an  atom;  these  laws  also  admit  of  absorption  of 
the  same  kinds  and  quantities,  i.e.  the  undoing  of  the 
emission.  I  apologise  for  an  apparent  poverty  of  illus- 
tration; it  must  be  remembered  that  many  properties  of 
a  body,  e.g.  temperature,  refer  to  its  constitution  as  a 
large  number  of  separate  atoms,  and  therefore  the  laws 
controlling  temperature  cannot  be  regarded  as  control- 
ling the  behaviour  of  a  single  individual. 

The  common  property  possessed  by  laws  governing 
the  individual  can  be  stated  more  clearly  by  a  reference 
to  time.  A  certain  sequence  of  states  running  from  past 
to  future  is  the  doing  of  an  event;  the  same  sequence 
running  from  future  to  past  is  the  undoing  of  it — be- 
cause in  the  latter  case  we  turn  round  the  sequence  so  as 
to  view  it  in  the  accustomed  manner  from  past  to  future. 
So  if  the  laws  of  Nature  are  indifferent  as  to  the  doing 
and  undoing  of  an  event,  they  must  be  indifferent  as 
to  a  direction  of  time  from  past  to  future.  That  is  their 
common  feature,  and  it  is  seen  at  once  when  (as 
usual)  the  laws  are  formulated  mathematically.  There 
is  no  more  distinction  between  past  and  future  than 
between  right  and  left.  In  algebraic  symbolism,  left  is 
— x,  right  is  +*;  past  is  — f,  future  is  +J.  This  holds 
for  all  laws  of  Nature  governing  the  behaviour  of  non- 
composite  individuals — the  "primary  laws",  as  we  shall 
call  them.  There  is  only  one  law  of  Nature — the  second 
law  of  thermodynamics — which  recognises  a  distinction 
between    past    and    future    more    profound    than    the 


SHUFFLING  67 

difference  of  plus  and  minus.  It  stands  aloof  from  all 
the  rest.  But  this  law  has  no  application  to  the  behaviour 
of  a  single  individual,  and  as  we  shall  see  later  its  sub- 
ject-matter is  the   random   element  in   a   crowd. 

Whatever  the  primary  laws  of  physics  may  say,  it  is 
obvious  to  ordinary  experience  that  there  is  a  distinction 
between  past  and  future  of  a  different  kind  from  the 
distinction  of  left  and  right.  In  The  Plattner  Story 
H.  G.  Wells  relates  how  a  man  strayed  into  the  fourth 
dimension  and  returned  with  left  and  right  interchanged. 
But  we  notice  that  this  interchange  is  not  the  theme  of 
the  story;  it  is  merely  a  corroborative  detail  to  give  an 
air  of  verisimilitude  to  the  adventure.  In  itself  the 
change  is  so  trivial  that  even  Mr.  Wells  cannot  weave 
a  romance  out  of  it.  But  if  the  man  had  come  back  with 
past  and  future  interchanged,  then  indeed  the  situation 
would  have  been  lively.  Mr.  Wells  in  The  Time-Machine 
and  Lewis  Carroll  in  Sylvie  and  Bruno  give  us  a  glimpse 
of  the  absurdities  which  occur  when  time  runs  back- 
wards. If  space  is  "looking-glassed"  the  world  con- 
tinues to  make  sense;  but  looking-glassed  time  has  an 
inherent  absurdity  which  turns  the  world-drama  into 
the  most  nonsensical  farce. 

Now  the  primary  laws  of  physics  taken  one  by  one 
all  declare  that  they  are  entirely  indifferent  as  to  which 
way  you  consider  time  to  be  progressing,  just  as  they 
are  indifferent  as  to  whether  you  view  the  world  from 
the  right  or  the  left.  This -is  true  of  the  classical  laws, 
the  relativity  laws,  and  even  of  the  quantum  laws.  It 
is  not  an  accidental  property;  the  reversibility  is  inherent 
in  the  whole  conceptual  scheme  in  which  these  laws 
find  a  place.  Thus  the  question  whether  the  world  does 
or  does  not  "make  sense"  is  outside  the  range  of  these 
laws.    We  have  to  appeal  to  the  one  outstanding  law — 


68     THE  RUNNING-DOWN  OF  THE  UNIVERSE 

the  second  law  of  thermodynamics — to  put  some  sense 
into  the  world.  It  opens  up  a  new  province  of  know- 
ledge, namely,  the  study  of  organisation;  and  it  is  in  con- 
nection with  organisation  that  a  direction  of  time-flow 
and  a  distinction  between  doing  and  undoing  appears  for 
the  first  time. 


Time's  Arrow,  The  great  thing  about  time  is  that  it  goes 
on.  But  this  is  an  aspect  of  it  which  the  physicist  some- 
times seems  inclined  to  neglect.  In  the  four-dimensional 
world  considered  in  the  last  chapter  the  events  past  and 
future  lie  spread  out  before  us  as  in  a  map.  The  events 
are  there  in  their  proper  spatial  and  temporal  relation; 
but  there  is  no  indication  that  they  undergo  what  has 
been  described  as  "the  formality  of  taking  place",  and 
the  question  of  their  doing  or  undoing  does  not  arise. 
We  see  in  the  map  the  path  from  past  to  future  or  from 
future  to  past;  but  there  is  no  signboard  to  indicate  that 
it  is  a  one-way  street.  Something  must  be  added  to 
the  geometrical  conceptions  comprised  in  Minkowski's 
world  before  it  becomes  a  complete  picture  of  the  world 
as  we  know  it.  We  may  appeal  to  consciousness  to  suffuse 
the  whole — to  turn  existence  into  happening,  being  into 
becoming.  But  first  let  us  note  that  the  picture  as  it 
stands  is  entirely  adequate  to  represent  those  primary 
laws  of  Nature  which,  as  we  have  seen,  are  indifferent 
to  a  direction  of  time.  Objection  has  sometimes  been 
felt  to  the  relativity  theory  because  its  four-dimensional 
picture  of  the  world  seems  to  overlook  the  directed 
character  of  time.  The  objection  is  scarcely  logical,  for 
the  theory  is  in  this  respect  no  better  and  no  worse  than 
its  predecessors.  The  classical  physicist  has  been  using 
without    misgiving    a    system    of    laws    which    do    not 


TIME'S  ARROW  69 

recognise  a  directed  time;  he  is  shocked  that  the  new 
picture  should  expose  this  so  glaringly. 

Without  any  mystic  appeal  to  consciousness  it  is 
possible  to  find  a  direction  of  time  on  the  four-dimen- 
sional map  by  a  study  of  organisation.  Let  us  draw  an 
arrow  arbitrarily.  If  as  we  follow  the  arrow  we  find 
more  and  more  of  the  random  element  in  the  state  of 
the  world,  then  the  arrow  is  pointing  towards  the  future; 
if  the  random  element  decreases  the  arrow  points 
towards  the  past.  That  is  the  only  distinction  known  to 
physics.  This  follows  at  once  if  our  fundamental  con- 
tention is  admitted  that  the  introduction  of  randomness 
is  the  only  thing  which  cannot  be  undone. 

I  shall  use  the  phrase  "time's  arrow"  to  express  this 
one-way  property  of  time  which  has  no  analogue  in 
space.  It  is  a  singularly  interesting  property  from  a 
philosophical  standpoint.     We  must  note  that — 

( 1 )  It  is  vividly  recognised  by  consciousness. 

(2)  It  is  equally  insisted  on  by  our  reasoning  faculty, 
which  tells  us  that  a  reversal  of  the  arrow  would  render 
the  external  world  nonsensical. 

(3)  It  makes  no  appearance  in  physical  science  except 
in  the  study  of  organisation  of  a  number  of  individuals. 
Here  the  arrow  indicates  the  direction  of  progressive 
increase  of  the  random  element. 

Let  us  now  consider  in  detail  how  a  random  element 
brings  the  irrevocable  into  the  world.  When  a  stone 
falls  it  acquires  kinetic  energy,  and  the  amount  of  the 
energy  is  just  that  which  would  be  required  to  lift  the 
stone  back  to  its  original  height.  By  suitable  arrange- 
ments the  kinetic  energy  can  be  made  to  perform  this 
task;  for  example,  if  the  stone  is  tied  to  a  string  it  can 
alternately  fall  and  reascend  like  a  pendulum.  But  if 
the  stone  hits  an  obstacle  its  kinetic  energy  is  converted 


70     THE  RUNNING-DOWN  OF  THE  UNIVERSE 

into  heat-energy.  There  is  still  the  same  quantity  of 
energy,  but  even  if  we  could  scrape  it  together  and  put 
it  through  an  engine  we  could  not  lift  the  stone  back 
with  it.  What  has  happened  to  make  the  energy  no 
longer  serviceable? 

Looking  microscopically  at  the  falling  stone  we  see 
an  enormous  multitude  of  molecules  moving  downwards 
with  equal  and  parallel  velocities — an  organised  motion 
like  the  march  of  a  regiment.  We  have  to  notice  two 
things,  the  energy  and  the  organisation  of  the  energy. 
To  return  to  its  original  height  the  stone  must  preserve 
both  of  them. 

When  the  stone  falls  on  a  sufficiently  elastic  surface 
the  motion  may  be  reversed  without  destroying  the 
organisation.  Each  molecule  is  turned  backwards  and  the 
whole  array  retires  in  good  order  to  the  starting-point — 

The  famous  Duke  of  York 

With  twenty  thousand  men, 
He  marched  them  up  to  the  top  of  the  hill 

And  marched  them  down  again. 

History  is  not  made  that  way.  But  what  usually  happens 
at  the  impact  is  that  the  molecules  suffer  more  or  less 
random  collisions  and  rebound  in  all  directions.  They 
no  longer  conspire  to  make  progress  in  any  one  direc- 
tion; they  have  lost  their  organisation.  Afterwards  they 
continue  to  collide  with  one  another  and  keep  changing 
their  directions  of  motion,  but  they  never  again  find  a 
common  purpose.  Organisation  cannot  be  brought 
about  by  continued  shuffling.  And  so,  although  the 
energy  remains  quantitatively  sufficient  (apart  from  un- 
avoidable leakage  which  we  suppose  made  good),  it 
cannot  lift  the  stone  back.  To  restore  the  stone  we  must 
supply  extraneous  energy  which  has  the  required 
amount  of  organisation. 


COINCIDENCES  71 

Here  a  point  arises  which  unfortunately  has  no 
analogy  in  the  shuffling  of  a  pack  of  cards.  No  one 
(except  a  conjurer)  can  throw  two  half-shuffled  packs 
into  a  hat  and  draw  out  one  pack  in  its  original  order 
and  one  pack  fully  shuffled.  But  we  can  and  do  put 
partly  disorganised  energy  into  a  steam-engine,  and 
draw  it  out  again  partly  as  fully  organised  energy  of 
motion  of  massive  bodies  and  partly  as  heat-energy  in 
a  state  of  still  worse  disorganisation.  Organisation  of 
energy  is  negotiable,  and  so  is  the  disorganisation  or 
random  element;  disorganisation  does  not  for  ever 
remain  attached  to  the  particular  store  of  energy  which 
first  suffered  it,  but  may  be  passed  on  elsewhere.  We 
cannot  here  enter  into  the  question  why  there  should  be 
a  difference  between  the  shuffling  of  energy  and  the 
shuffling  of  material  objects;  but  it  is  necessary  to  use 
some  caution  in  applying  the  analogy  on  account  of  this 
difference.  As  regards  heat-energy  the  temperature  is 
the  measure  of  its  degree  of  organisation;  the  lower  the 
temperature,  the  greater  the   disorganisation. 

Coincidences,  There  are  such  things  as  chance  coinci- 
dences; that  is  to  say,  chance  can  deceive  us  by  bringing 
about  conditions  which  look  very  unlike  chance.  In 
particular  chance  might  imitate  organisation,  whereas 
we  have  taken  organisation  to  be  the  antithesis  o{ 
chance  or,  as  we  have  called  it,  the  "random  element". 
This  threat  to  our  conclusions  is,  however,  not  very 
serious.     There  is  safety  in  numbers. 

Suppose  that  you  have  a  vessel  divided  by  a  partition 
into  two  halves,  one  compartment  containing  air  and 
the  other  empty.  You  withdraw  the  partition.  For  the 
moment  all  the  molecules  of  air  are  in  one  half  of  the 
vessel;  a  fraction  of  a  second  later  they  are  spread  over 


72     THE  RUNNING-DOWN  OF  THE  UNIVERSE 

the  whole  vessel  and  remain  so  ever  afterwards.  The 
molecules  will  not  return  to  one  half  of  the  vessel;  the 
spreading  cannot  be  undone — unless  other  material  is 
introduced  into  the  problem  to  serve  as  a  scapegoat  for 
the  disorganisation  and  carry  off  the  random  element 
elsewhere.  This  occurrence  can  serve  as  a  criterion  to 
distinguish  past  and  future  time.  If  you  observe  first 
the  molecules  spread  through  the  vessel  and  (as  it 
seems  to  you)  an  instant  later  the  molecules  all  in  one 
half  of  it — then  your  consciousness  is  going  backwards, 
and  you  had  better  consult  a  doctor. 

Now  each  molecule  is  wandering  round  the  vessel 
with  no  preference  for  one  part  rather  than  the  other. 
On  the  average  it  spends  half  its  time  in  one  compart- 
ment and  half  in  the  other.  There  is  a  faint  possibility 
that  at  one  moment  all  the  molecules  might  in  this  way 
happen  to  be  visiting  the  one  half  of  the  vessel.  You 
will  easily  calculate  that  if  n  is  the  number  of  molecules 
(roughly  a  quadrillion)  the  chance  of  this  happening  is 
( y2  )n.  The  reason  why  we  ignore  this  chance  may  be  seen 
by  a  rather  classical  illustration.  If  I  let  my  fingers 
wander  idly  over  the  keys  of  a  typewriter  it  might 
happen  that  my  screed  made  an  intelligible  sentence. 
If  an  army  of  monkeys  were  strumming  on  typewriters 
they  might  write  all  the  books  in  the  British  Museum. 
The  chance  of  their  doing  so  is  decidedly  more  favour- 
able than  the  chance  of  the  molecules  returning  to  one 
half  of  the  vessel. 

When  numbers  are  large,  chance  is  the  best  warrant 
for  certainty.  Happily  in  the  study  of  molecules  and 
energy  and  radiation  in  bulk  we  have  to  deal  with  a 
vast  population,  and  we  reach  a  certainty  which  does 
not  always  reward  the  expectations  of  those  who  court 
the  fickle  goddess. 


COINCIDENCES  73 

In  one  sense  the  chance  of  the  molecules  returning 
to  one  half  of  the  vessel  is  too  absurdly  small  to  think 
about.  Yet  in  science  we  think  about  it  a  great  deal, 
because  it  gives  a  measure  of  the  irrevocable  mischief 
we  did  when  we  casually  removed  the  partition.  Even 
if  we  had  good  reasons  for  wanting  the  gas  to  fill  the 
vessel  there  was  no  need  to  waste  the  organisation;  as 
we  have  mentioned,  it  is  negotiable  and  might  have  been 
passed  on  somewhere  where  it  was  useful.*  When  the 
gas  was  released  and  began  to  spread  across  the  vessel, 
say  from  left  to  right,  there  was  no  immediate  increase 
of  the  random  element.  In  order  to  spread  from  left  to 
right,  left-to-right  velocities  of  the  molecules  must  have 
preponderated,  that  is  to  say  the  motion  was  partly 
organised.  Organisation  of  position  was  replaced  by 
organisation  of  motion.  A  moment  later  the  molecules 
struck  the  farther  wall  of  the  vessel  and  the  random 
element  began  to  increase.  But,  before  it  was  destroyed, 
the  left-to-right  organisation  of  molecular  velocities  was 
the  exact  numerical  equivalent  of  the  lost  organisation 
in  space.  By  that  we  mean  that  the  chance  against  the 
left-to-right  preponderance  of  velocity  occurring  by 
accident  is  the  same  as  the  chance  against  segregation 
in  one  half  of  the  vessel  occurring  by  accident. 

The  adverse  chance  here  mentioned  is  a  preposterous 
number  which  (written  in  the  usual  decimal  notation) 
would  fill  all  the  books  in  the  world  many  times  over. 
We  are  not  interested  in  it  as  a  practical  contingency; 
but  we  are  interested  in  the  fact  that  it  is  definite.  It 
raises  "organisation"  from  a  vague  descriptive  epithet 
to  one  of  the  measurable  quantities  of  exact  science. 
We   are   confronted  with   many   kinds   of   organisation. 

*  If   the   gas   in    expanding    had    been   made    to    move    a    piston,    the 
organisation  would  have  passed  into  the  motion  of  the  piston. 


74     THE  RUNNING-DOWN  OF  THE  UNIVERSE 

The  uniform  march  of  a  regiment  is  not  the  only  form 
of  organised  motion;  the  organised  evolutions  of  a 
stage  chorus  have  their  natural  analogue  in  sound  waves. 
A  common  measure  can  now  be  applied  to  all  forms 
of  organisation.  Any  loss  of  organisation  is  equitably 
measured  by  the  chance  against  its  recovery  by  an  acci- 
dental coincidence.  The  chance  is  absurd  regarded  as 
a  contingency,  but  it  is  precise  as  a  measure. 

The  practical  measure  of  the  random  element  which 
can  increase  in  the  universe  but  can  never  decrease  is 
called  entropy.  Measuring  by  entropy  is  the  same  as 
measuring  by  the  chance  explained  in  the  last  paragraph, 
only  the  unmanageably  large  numbers  are  transformed 
(by  a  simple  formula)  into  a  more  convenient  scale  of 
reckoning.  Entropy  continually  increases.  We  can, 
by  isolating  parts  of  the  world  and  postulating  rather 
idealised  conditions  in  our  problems,  arrest  the  increase, 
but  we  cannot  turn  it  into  a  decrease.  That  would 
involve  something  much  worse  than  a  violation  of  an 
ordinary  law  of  Nature,  namely,  an  improbable  coinci- 
dence. The  law  that  entropy  always  increases — the 
second  law  of  thermodynamics — holds,  I  think,  the 
supreme  position  among  the  laws  of  Nature.  If  someone 
points  out  to  you  that  your  pet  theory  of  the  universe 
is  in  disagreement  with  Maxwell's  equations — then  so 
much  the  worse  for  Maxwell's  equations.  If  it  is  found 
to  be  contradicted  by  observation — well,  these  experi- 
mentalists do  bungle  things  sometimes.  But  if  your 
theory  is  found  to  be  against  the  second  law  of  thermo- 
dynamics I  can  give  you  no  hope;  there  is  nothing  for 
it  but  to  collapse  in  deepest  humiliation.  This  exaltation 
of  the  second  law  is  not  unreasonable.  There  are  other 
laws  which  we  have  strong  reason  to  believe  in,  and  we 
feel   that   a    hypothesis   which   violates   them   is   highly 


PRIMARY  AND  SECONDARY  LAW]  75 

improbable;  but  the  improbability  is  vague  and  does 
not  confront  us  as  a  paralysing  array  of  figures,  whereas 
the  chance  against  a  breach  of  the  second  law  (i.e. 
against  a  decrease  of  the  random  element)  can  be  stated 
in  figures  which  are  overwhelming. 

I  wish  I  could  convey  to  you  the  amazing  power  of 
this  conception  of  entropy  in  scientific  research.  From 
the  property  that  entropy  must  always  increase,  practical 
methods  of  measuring  it  have  been  found.  The  chain 
of  deductions  from  this  simple  law  have  been  almost 
illimitable;  and  it  has  been  equally  successful  in  con- 
nection with  the  most  recondite  problems  of  theoretical 
physics  and  the  practical  tasks  of  the  engineer.  Its 
special  feature  is  that  the  conclusions  are  independent 
of  the  nature  of  the  microscopical  processes  that  are 
going  on.  It  is  not  concerned  with  the  nature  of  the 
individual;  it  is  interested  in  him  only  as  a  component 
of  a  crowd.  Therefore  the  method  is  applicable  in 
fields  of  research  where  our  ignorance  has  scarcely  begun 
to  lift,  and  we  have  no  hesitation  in  applying  it  to  prob- 
lems of  the  quantum  theory,  although  the  mechanism 
of  the  individual  quantum  process  is  unknown  and  at 
present  unimaginable. 

Primary  and  Secondary  Law.  I  have  called  the  laws 
controlling  the  behaviour  of  single  individuals  "primary 
laws",  implying  that  the  second  law  of  thermodynamics, 
although  a  recognised  law  of  Nature,  is  in  some  sense  a 
secondary  law.  This  distinction  can  now  be  placed  on 
a  regular  footing.  Some  things  never  happen  in  the 
physical  world  because  they  are  impossible;  others 
because  they  are  too  improbable.  The  laws  which  forbid 
the  first  are  the  primary  laws;  the  laws  which  forbid  the 
second  are  the  secondary  laws.     It  has  been  the  convic- 


76     THE  RUNNING-DOWN  OF  THE  UNIVERSE 

tion  of  nearly  all  physicists*  that  at  the  root  of  every- 
thing there  is  a  complete  scheme  of  primary  law  govern- 
ing the  career  of  every  particle  or  constituent  of  the 
world  with  an  iron  determinism.  This  primary  scheme 
is  all-sufficing,  for,  since  it  fixes  the  history  of  every 
constituent  of  the  world,  it  fixes  the  whole  world- 
history. 

But  for  all  its  completeness  primary  law  does  not 
answer  every  question  about  Nature  which  we  might 
reasonably  wish  to  put.  Can  a  universe  evolve  back- 
wards, i.e.  develop  in  the  opposite  way  to  our  own 
system?  Primary  law,  being  indifferent  to  a  time- 
direction,  replies,  "Yes,  it  is  not  impossible".  Secondary 
law  replies,  "No,  it  is  too  improbable".  The  answers  are 
not  really  in  conflict;  but  the  first,  though  true,  rather 
misses  the  point.  This  is  typical  of  some  much  more 
commonplace  queries.  If  I  put  this  saucepan  of  water 
on  this  fire,  will  the  water  boil?  Primary  law  can  answer 
definitely  if  it  is  given  the  chance;  but  it  must  be 
understood  that  "this"  translated  into  mathematics 
means  a  specification  of  the  positions,  motions,  etc.,  of 
some  quadrillions  of  particles  and  elements  of  energy. 
So  in  practice  the  question  answered  is  not  quite  the 
one  that;  is  asked:  If  I  put  a  saucepan  resembling  this 
one  in  a  few  major  respects  on  a  fire,  will  the  water 
boil?  Primary  law  replies,  "It  may  boil;  it  may  freeze;  it 
may  do  pretty  well  anything.  The  details  given  are  insuf- 
ficient to  exclude  any  result  as  impossible."  Secondary 
law  replies  plainly,  "It  will  boil  because  it  is  too  im- 
probable that  it  should  do  anything  else."  Secondary 
law  is  not  in  conflict  with  primary  law,  nor  can  we  re- 
gard it  as  essential  to  complete  a  scheme  of  law  already 

♦There  are,  however,  others  beside  myself  who  have  recently  begun  to 
question   it. 


THERMODYNAMICAL  EQUILIBRIUM  77 

complete  in  itself.  It  results  from  a  different  '(and 
rather  more  practical)  conception  of  the  aim  of  our 
traffic  with  the  secrets  of  Nature. 

The  question  whether  the  second  law  of  thermo- 
dynamics and  other  statistical  laws  are  mathematical 
deductions  from  the  primary  laws,  presenting  their 
results  in  a  conveniently  usable  form,  is  difficult  to 
answer;  but  I  think  it  is  generally  considered  that  there 
is  an  unbridgeable  hiatus.  At  the  bottom  of  all  the 
questions  settled  by  secondary  law  there  is  an  elusive 
conception  of  ua  priori  probability  of  states  of  the 
world"  which  involves  an  essentially  different  attitude  to 
knowledge  from  that  presupposed  in  the  construction  of 
the  scheme  of  primary  law. 

Thermo  dynamical  Equilibrium.  Progress  of  time  intro- 
duces more  and  more  of  the  random  element  into  the 
constitution  of  the  world.  There  is  less  of  chance  about 
the  physical  universe  to-day  than  there  will  be  to-mor- 
row. It  is  curious  that  in  this  very  matter-of-fact 
branch  of  physics,  developed  primarily  because  of  its 
importance  for  engineers,  we  can  scarcely  avoid  express- 
ing ourselves  in  teleological  language.  We  admit  that 
the  world  contains  both  chance  and  design,  or  at  any 
rate  chance  and  the  antithesis  of  chance.  This  antithe- 
sis is  emphasised  by  our  method  of  measurement  of 
entropy;  we  assign  to  the  organisation  or  non-chance 
element  a  measure  which  is,*  so  to  speak,  proportional 
to  the  strength  of  our  disbelief  in  a  chance  origin  for  it. 
"A  fortuitous  concourse  of  atoms" — that  bugbear  of 
the  theologian — has  a  very  harmless  place  in  orthodox 
physics.  The  physicist  is  acquainted  with  it  as  a  much- 
prized  rarity.  Its  properties  are  very  distinctive,  and 
unlike    those    of   the   physical   world    in   general.      The 


78     THE  RUNNING-DOWN  OF  THE  UNIVERSE 

scientific  name  for  a  fortuitous  concourse  of  atoms  is 
"thermodynamical   equilibrium". 

Thermodynamical  equilibrium  is  the  other  case 
which  we  promised  to  consider  in  which  no  increase  in 
the  random  element  can  occur,  namely,  that  in  which  the 
shuffling  is  already  as  thorough  as  possible.  We  must 
isolate  a  region  of  the  universe,  arranging  that  no 
energy  can  enter  or  leave  it,  or  at  least  that  any  bound- 
ary effects  are  precisely  compensated.  The  conditions 
are  ideal,  but  they  can  be  reproduced  with  sufficient 
approximation  to  make  the  ideal  problem  relevant  to 
practical  experiment.  A  region  in  the  deep  interior  of 
a  star  is  an  almost  perfect  example  of  thermodynamical 
equilibrium.  Under  these  isolated  conditions  the  energy 
will  be  shuffled  as  it  is  bandied  from  matter  to  aether 
and  back  again,  and  very  soon  the  shuffling  will  be 
complete. 

The  possibility  of  the  shuffling  becoming  complete 
is  significant.  If  after  shuffling  the  pack  you  tear  each 
card  in  two,  a  further  shuffling  of  the  half-cards  becomes 
possible.  Tear  the  cards  again  and  again;  each  time 
there  is  further  scope  for  the  random  element  to 
increase.  With  infinite  divisibility  there  can  be  no  end 
to  the  shuffling.  The  experimental  fact  that  a  definite 
state  of  equilibrium  is  rapidly  reached  indicates  that 
energy  is  not  infinitely  divisible,  or  at  least  that  it  is  not 
infinitely  divided  in  the  natural  processes  of  shuffling. 
Historically  this  is  the  result  from  which  the  quantum 
theory  first  arose.  We  shall  return  to  it  in  a  later 
chapter. 

In  such  a  region  we  lose  time's  arrow.  You  remember 
that  the  arrow  points  in  the  direction  of  increase  of 
the  random  element.  When  the  random  element  has 
reached  its  limit  and  become  steady  the  arrow  does  not 


THERMODYNAMICAL  EQUILIBRIUM  79 

know  which  way  to  point.  It  would  not  be  true  to  say 
that  such  a  region  is  timeless;  the  atoms  vibrate  as  usual 
like  little  clocks;  by  them  we  can  measure  speeds  and 
durations.  Time  is  still  there  and  retains  its  ordinary 
properties,  but  it  has  lost  its  arrow;  like  space  it  extends, 
but  it  does  not  "go  on". 

This  raises  the  important  question,  Is  the  random 
element  (measured  by  the  criterion  of  probability 
already  discussed)  the  only  feature  of  the  physical  world 
which  can  furnish  time  with  an  arrow?  Up  to  the 
present  we  have  concluded  that  no  arrow  can  be  found 
from  the  behaviour  of  isolated  individuals,  but  there  is 
scope  for  further  search  among  the  properties  of  crowds 
beyond  the  property  represented  by  entropy.  To  give 
an  illustration  which  is  perhaps  not  quite  so  fantastic 
as  it  sounds,  Might  not  the  assemblage  become  more 
and  more  beautiful  (according  to  some  agreed  aesthetic 
standard)  as  time  proceeds?*  The  question  is  answered 
by  another  important  law  of  Nature  which  runs — 

Nothing  in  the  statistics  of  an  assemblage  can  distin- 
guish a  direction  of  time  when  entropy  fails  to  distinguish 
one. 

I  think  that  although  this  law  was  only  discovered  in 
the  last  few  years  there  is  no  serious  doubt  as  to  its 
truth.  It  is  accepted  as  fundamental  in  all  modern 
studies  of  atoms  and  radiation  and  has  proved  to  be  one 
of  the  most  powerful  weapons  of  progress  in  such 
researches.  It  is,  of  course,  one  of  the  secondary  laws. 
It  does  not  seem  to  be  rigorously  deducible  from  the 
second  law  of  thermodynamics,  and  presumably  must 
be  regarded  as  an  additional  secondary  law.t 

*  In  a  kaleidoscope  the  shuffling  is  soon  complete  and  all  the  patterns 
are  equal  as  regards  random  element,  but  they  differ  greatly  in  elegance. 

f  The  law  is  so  much  disguised  in  the  above  enunciation  that  I  must 
explain  to  the  advanced  reader  that  I  am  referring  to  "the  Principle  of 


80     THE  RUNNING-DOWN  OF  THE  UNIVERSE 

The  conclusion  is  that  whereas  other  statistical 
characters  besides  entropy  might  perhaps  be  used  to 
discriminate  time's  arrow,  they  can  only  succeed  when 
it  succeeds  and  they  fail  when  it  fails.  Therefore  they 
cannot  be  regarded  as  independent  tests.  So  far  as 
physics  is  concerned  time's  arrow  is  a  property  of 
entropy   alone. 

Are  Space  and  Time  Infinite?  I  suppose  that  everyone 
has  at  some  time  plagued  his  imagination  with  the 
question,  Is  there  an  end  to  space?  If  space  comes  to 
an  end,  what  is  beyond  the  end?  On  the  other  hand  the 
idea  that  there  is  no  end,  but  space  beyond  space  for 
ever,  is  inconceivable.  And  so  the  imagination  is  tossed 
to  and  fro  in  a  dilemma.  Prior  to  the  relativity  theory 
the  orthodox  view  was  that  space  is  infinite.  No  one 
can  conceive  infinite  space;  wre  had  to  be  content  to 
admit  in  the  physical  world  an  inconceivable  concep- 
tion— disquieting  but  not  necessarily  illogical.  Einstein's 
theory  now  offers  a  way  out  of  the  dilemma.  Is  space 
infinite,  or  does  it  come  to  an  end?  Neither.  Space 
is  finite  but  it  has  no  end;  "finite  but  unbounded" 
is  the  usual  phrase. 

Infinite  space  cannot  be  conceived  by  anybody; 
finite  but  unbounded  space  is  difficult  to  conceive  but 
not  impossible.  I  shall  not  expect  you  to  conceive  it; 
but  you  can  try.     Think  first  of  a  circle;  or,  rather,  not 


Detailed  Balancing."  This  principle  asserts  that  to  every  type  of  process 
(however  minutely  particularised)  there  is  a  converse  process,  and  in 
thermodynamical  equilibrium  direct  and  converse  processes  occur  with 
equal  frequency.  Thus  every  statistical  enumeration  of  the  processes  is 
unaltered  by  reversing  the  time-direction,  i.e.  interchanging  direct  and 
converse  processes.  Hence  there  can  be  no  statistical  criterion  for  a 
direction  of  time  when  there  is  thermodynamical  equilibrium,  i.e.  when 
entropy  is  steady  and  ceases  to  indicate  time's  arrow. 


ARE  SPACE  AND  TIME  INFINITE?  81 

the  circle,  but  the  line  forming  its  circumference.  This 
is  a  finite  but  endless  line.  Next  think  of  a  sphere — the 
surface  of  a  sphere — that  also  is  a  region  which  is 
finite  but  unbounded.  The  surface  of  this  earth  never 
comes  to  a  boundary;  there  is  always  some  country 
beyond  the  point  you  have  reached;  all  the  same  there 
is  not  an  infinite  amount  of  room  on  the  earth.  Now  go 
one  dimension  more;  circle,  sphere — the  next  thing. 
Got  that?  Now  for  the  real  difficulty.  Keep  a  tight  hold 
of  the  skin  of  this  hypersphere  and  imagine  that  the 
inside  is  not  there  at  all — that  the  skin  exists  without 
the  inside.     That  is  finite  but  unbounded  space. 

No;  I  don't  think  you  have  quite  kept  hold  of  the 
conception.  You  overbalanced  just  at  the  end.  It  was 
not  the  adding  of  one  more  dimension  that  was  the  real 
difficulty;  it  was  the  final  taking  away  of  a  dimension 
that  did  it.  I  will  tell  you  what  is  stopping  you.  You 
are  using  a  conception  of  space  which  must  have 
originated  many  million  years  ago  and  has  become 
rather  firmly  embedded  in  human  thought.  But  the 
space  of  physics  ought  not  to  be  dominated  by  this 
creation  of  the  dawning  mind  of  an  enterprising  ape. 
Space  is  not  necessarily  like  this  conception;  it  is  like — 
whatever  we  find  from  experiment  it  is  like.  Now  the 
features  of  space  which  we  discover  by  experiment  are 
extensions,  i.e.  lengths  and  distances.  So  space  is  like 
a  network  of  distances.  Distances  are  linkages  whose 
intrinsic  nature  is  inscrutable;  we  do  not  deny  the 
inscrutability  when  we  apply  measure  numbers  to  them 
— 2  yards,  5  miles,  etc. — as  a  kind  of  code  distinction. 
We  cannot  predict  out  of  our  inner  consciousness  the 
laws  by  which  code-numbers  are  distributed  among  the 
different  linkages  of  the  network,  any  more  than  we 
can  predict  how  the  code-numbers  for  electromagnetic 


82     THE  RUNNING-DOWN  OF  THE  UNIVERSE 

force  are  distributed.  Both  are  a  matter  for  experi- 
ment. 

If  we  go  a  very  long  way  to  a  point  A  in  one  direction 
through  the  universe  and  a  very  long  way  to  a  point  B 
in  the  opposite  direction,  it  is  believed  that  between 
A  and  B  there  exists  a  linkage  of  the  kind  indicated  by 
a  very  small  code-number;  in  other  words  these  points 
reached  by  travelling  vast  distances  in  opposite  directions 
would  be  found  experimentally  to  be  close  together. 
Why  not?  This  happens  when  we  travel  east  and  west 
on  the  earth.  It  is  true  that  our  traditional  inflexible 
conception  of  space  refuses  to  admit  it;  but  there  was 
once  a  traditional  conception  of  the  earth  which  refused 
to  admit  circumnavigation.  In  our  approach  to  the 
conception  of  spherical  space  the  difficult  part  was  to 
destroy  the  inside  of  the  hypersphere  leaving  only  its 
three-dimensional  surface  existing.  I  do  not  think  that 
is  so  difficult  when  we  conceive  space  as  a  network  of 
distances.  The  network  over  the  surface  constitutes  a 
self-supporting  system  of  linkage  which  can  be  con- 
templated without  reference  to  extraneous  linkages.  We 
can  knock  away  the  constructional  scaffolding  which 
helped  us  to  approach  the  conception  of  this  kind  of 
network  of  distances  without  endangering  the  con- 
ception. 

We  must  realise  that  a  scheme  of  distribution  of 
inscrutable  relations  linking  points  to  one  another  is  not 
bound  to  follow  any  particular  preconceived  plan,  so 
that  there  can  be  no  obstacle  to  the  acceptance  of  any 
scheme  indicated  by  experiment. 

We  do  not  yet  know  what  is  the  radius  of  spherical 
space;  it  must,  of  course,  be  exceedingly  great  com- 
pared with  ordinary  standards.  On  rather  insecure 
evidence   it  has   been  estimated  to   be  not  many  times 


ARE  SPACE  AND  TIME  INFINITE?  83 

greater  than  the  distance  of  the  furthest  known  nebulae. 
But  the  boundlessness  has  nothing  to  do  with  the 
bigness.  Space  is  boundless  by  re-entrant  form  not  by 
great  extension.  That  which  is  is  a  shell  floating  in  the 
infinitude  of  that  which  is  not.  We  say  with  Hamlet, 
"I  could  be  bounded  in  a  nutshell  and  count  myself  a 
king  of  infinite  space". 

But  the  nightmare  of  infinity  still  arises  in  regard  to 
time.  The  world  is  closed  in  its  space  dimensions  like 
a  sphere,  but  it  is  open  at  both  ends  in  the  time  dimen- 
sion. There  is  a  bending  round  by  which  East  ulti- 
mately becomes  West,  but  no  bending  by  which  Before 
ultimately  becomes  After. 

I  am  not  sure  that  I  am  logical  but  I  cannot  feel  the 
difficulty  of  an  infinite  future  time  very  seriously.  The 
difficulty  about  A.D.  co  will  not  happen  until  we  reach 
A.D.  00,  and  presumably  in  order  to  reach  A.D.  00  the 
difficulty  must  first  have  been  surmounted.  It  should 
also  be  noted  that  according  to  the  second  law  of  thermo- 
dynamics the  whole  universe  will  reach  thermodynamical 
equilibrium  at  a  not  infinitely  remote  date  in  the  future. 
Time's  arrow  will  then  be  lost  altogether  and  the  whole 
conception  of  progress  towards  a  future  fades  away. 

But  the  difficulty  of  an  infinite  past  is  appalling.  It 
is  inconceivable  that  we  are  the  heirs  of  an  infinite  time 
of  preparation;  it  is  not  less  inconceivable  that  there  was 
once  a  moment  with  no  moment  preceding  it. 

This  dilemma  of  the  beginning  of  time  would  worry 
us  more  were  it  not  shut  out  by  another  overwhelming 
difficulty  lying  between  us  and  the  infinite  past.  We 
have  been  studying  the  running-down  of  the  universe; 
if  our  views  are  right,  somewhere  between  the  beginning 
of  time  and  the  present  day  we  must  place  the  winding 
up  of  the  universe. 


$4     THE  RUNNING-DOWN  OF  THE  UNIVERSE 

Travelling  backwards  into  the  past  we  find  a  world 
with  more  and  more  organisation.  If  there  is  no  barrier 
to  stop  us  earlier  we  must  reach  a  moment  when  the 
energy  of  the  world  was  wholly  organised  with  none  of 
the  random  element  in  it.  It  is  impossible  to  go  back 
any  further  under  the  present  system  of  natural  law. 
I  do  not  think  the  phrase  "wholly  organised"  begs  the 
question.  The  organisation,  we  are  concerned  with  is 
exactly  definable,  and  there  is  a  limit  at  which  it  becomes 
perfect.  There  is  not  an  infinite  series  of  states  of 
higher  and  still  higher  organisation;  nor,  I  think,  is  the 
limit  one  which  is  ultimately  approached  more  and  more 
slowly.  Complete  organisation  does  not  tend  to  be 
more  immune  from  loss  than  incomplete  organisation. 

There  is  no  doubt  that  the  scheme  of  physics  as  it 
has  stood  for  the  last  three-quarters  of  a  century  postu- 
lates a  date  at  which  either  the  entities  of  the  universe 
were  created  in  a  state  of  high  organisation,  or  pre- 
existing entities  were  endowed  with  that  organisation 
which  they  have  been  squandering  ever  since.  More- 
over, this  organisation  is  admittedly  the  antithesis  of 
chance.  It  is  something  which  could  not  occur  for- 
tuitously. 

This  has  long  been  used  as  an  argument  against  a 
too  aggressive  materialism.  It  has  been  quoted  as 
scientific  proof  of  the  intervention  of  the  Creator  at  a 
time  not  infinitely  remote  from  to-day.  But  I  am  not 
advocating  that  we  drew  any  hasty  conclusions  from  it. 
Scientists  and  theologians  alike  must  regard  as  some- 
what crude  the  naive  theological  doctrine  which 
(suitably  disguised)  is  at  present  to  be  found  in  every 
textbook  of  thermodynamics,  namely  that  some  billions 
of  years  ago  God  wound  up  the  material  universe  and 
has  left  it  to  chance  ever  since.     This  should  be  regarded 


ARE  SPACE  AND  TIME  INFINITE?  85 

as  the  working-hypothesis  of  thermodynamics  rather 
than  its  declaration  of  faith.  It  is  one  of  those  conclu- 
sions from  which  we  can  see  no  logical  escape — only 
it  suffers  from  the  drawback  that  it  is  incredible.  As  a 
scientist  I  simply  do  not  believe  that  the  present  order 
of  things  started  off  with  a  bang;  unscientifically  I  feel 
equally  unwilling  to  accept  the  implied  discontinuity  in 
the  divine  nature.  But  I  can  make  no  suggestion  to 
evade  the  deadlock. 

Turning  again  to  the  other  end  of  time,  there  is  one 
school  of  thought  which  finds  very  repugnant  the  idea 
of  a  wearing  out  of  the  world.  This  school  is  attracted 
by  various  theories  of  rejuvenescence.  Its  mascot  is  the 
Phoenix.  Stars  grow  cold  and  die  out.  May  not  two 
dead  stars  collide,  and  be  turned  by  the  energy  of  the 
shock  into  fiery  vapour  from  which  a  new  sun — with 
planets  and  with  life — is  born?  This  theory  very 
prevalent  in  the  last  century  is  no  longer  contemplated 
seriously  by  astronomers.  There  is  evidence  that  the 
present  stars  at  any  rate  are  products  of  one  evolutionary 
process  which  swept  across  primordial  matter  and 
caused  it  to  aggregate ;  they  were  not  formed  individually 
by  haphazard  collisions  having  no  particular  time  con- 
nection with  one  another.  But  the  Phoenix  complex  is 
still  active.  Matter,  we  believe,  is  gradually  destroyed 
and  its  energy  set  free  in  radiation.  Is  there  no  coun- 
ter-process by  which  radiation  collects  in  space,  evolves 
into  electrons  and  protons,  and  begins  star-building  all 
over  again?  This  is  pure  speculation  and  there  is  not 
much  to  be  said  on  one;  side  or  the  other  as  to  its  truth. 
But  I  would  mildly  criticise  the  mental  outlook  which 
wishes  it  to  be  true.  However  much  we  eliminate  the 
minor  extravagances  of  Nature,  we  do  not  by  these 
theories  stop  the  inexorable  running-down  of  the  world 


86     THE  RUNNING-DOWN  OF  THE  UNIVERSE 

by  loss  of  organisation  and  increase  of  the  random 
element.  Whoever  wishes  for  a  universe  which  can 
continue  indefinitely  in  'activity  must  lead  a  crusade 
against  the  second  law  of  thermodynamics;  the  possi- 
bility of  re-formation  of  matter  from  radiation  is  not 
crucial  and  we  can  await  conclusions  with  some  indif- 
ference. 

At  present  we  can  see  no  way  in  which  an  attack  on 
the  second  law  of  thermodynamics  could  possibly 
succeed,  and  I  confess  that  personally  I  have  no  great 
desire  that  it  should  succeed  in  averting  the  final 
running-down  of  the  universe.  I  am  no  Phoenix 
worshipper.  This  is  a  topic  on  which  science  is  silent, 
and  all  that  one  can  say  is  prejudice.  But  since  prejudice 
in  favour  of  a  never-ending  cycle  of  rebirth  of  matter 
and  worlds  is  often  vocal,  I  may  perhaps  give  voice  to 
the  opposite  prejudice.  I  would  feel  more  content  that 
the  universe  should  accomplish  some  great  scheme  of 
evolution  and,  having  achieved  whatever  may  be 
achieved,  lapse  back  into  chaotic  changelessness,  than 
that  its  purpose  should  be  banalised  by  continual 
repetition.  I  am  an  Evolutionist,  not  a  Multiplicationist. 
It  seems  rather  stupid  to  keep  doing  the  same  thing 
over  and  over  again. 


Chapter  V 
"BECOMING" 

Linkage  of  Entropy  with  Becoming.  When  you  say  to 
yourself,  "Every  day  I  grow  better  and  better",  science 
churlishly  replies — 

"I  see  no  signs  of  it.  I  see  you  extended  as  a  four- 
dimensional  worm  in  space-time;  and,  although  goodness 
is  not  strictly  within  my  province,  I  will  grant  that  one 
end  of  you  is  better  than  the  other.  But  whether  you 
grow  better  or  worse  depends  on  which  way  up  I  hold 
you.  There  is  in  your  consciousness  an  idea  of  growth 
or  'becoming'  which,  if  it  is  not  illusory,  implies  that 
you  have  a  label  'This  side  up'.  I  have  searched  for 
such  a  label  all  through  the  physical  world  and  can  find 
no  trace  of  it,  so  I  strongly  suspect  that  the  label  is 
non-existent  in  the  world  of  reality." 

That  is  the  reply  of  science  comprised  in  primary 
law.  Taking  account  of  secondary  law,  the  reply  is 
modified  a  little,  though  it  is  still  none  too  gracious — 

"I  have  looked  again  and,  in  the  course  of  studying 
a  property  called  entropy,  I  find  that  the  physical  world 
is  marked  with  an  arrow  which  may  possibly  be  in- 
tended to  indicate  which  way  up  it  should  be  regarded. 
With  that  orientation  I  find  that  you  really  do  grow 
better.  Or,  to  speak  precisely,  your  good  end  is  in  the 
part  of  the  world  with  most  entropy  and  your  bad  end 
in  the  part  with  least.  Why  this  arrangement  should 
be  considered  more  creditable  than  that  of  your  neigh- 
bour who  has  his  good  and  bad  ends  the  other  way 
round,   I  cannot  imagine." 

A    problem    here     rises    before    us    concerning    the 

87 


88  "BECOMING" 

linkage  of  the  symbolic  world  of  physics  to  the  world 
of  familiar  experience.  As  explained  in  the  Introduction 
this  question  of  linkage  remains  over  at  the  end  of  the 
strictly  physical  investigations.  Our  present  problem 
is  to  understand  the  linkage  between  entropy  which 
provides  time's  arrow  in  the  symbolic  world  and  the 
experience  of  growing  or  becoming  which  is  the  inter- 
pretation of  time's  arrow  in  the  familiar  world.  We 
have,  I  think,  shown  exhaustively  in  the  last  chapter  that 
the  former  is  the  only  scientific  counterpart  to  the  latter. 

But  in  treating  change  of  entropy  as  a  symbolic 
equivalent  for  the  moving  on  of  time  familiar  to  our 
minds  a  double  difficulty  arises.  Firstly,  the  symbol 
seems  to  be  of  inappropriate  nature;  it  is  an  elaborate 
mathematical  construct,  whereas  we  should  expect  so 
fundamental  a  conception  as  "becoming"  to  be  among 
the  elementary  indefinables — the  A  B  C  of  physics. 
Secondly,  a  symbol  does  not  seem  to  be  quite  what  is 
wanted;  we  want  a  significance  which  can  scarcely  be 
conveyed  by  a  symbol  of  the  customary  metrical  type — 
the  recognition  of  a  dynamic  quality  in  external  Nature. 
We  do  not  "put  sense  into  the  world"  merely  by 
recognising  that  one  end  of  it  is  more  random  than  the 
other;  we  have  to  put  a  genuine  significance  of  "be- 
coming" into  it  and  not  an  artificial  symbolic  substitute. 

The  linkage  of  entropy-change  to  "becoming" 
presents  features  unlike  every  other  problem  of  paral- 
lelism of  the  scientific  and  familiar  worlds.  The  usual 
relation  is  illustrated  by  the  familiar  perception  of 
colour  and  its  scientific  equivalent  electromagnetic  wave- 
length. Here  there  is  no  question  of  resemblance 
between  the  underlying  physical  cause  and  the  mental 
sensation  which  arises.  All  that  we  can  require  of 
the   symbolic   counterpart   of   colour   is   that   it  shall   be 


ENTROPY  AND  BECOMING  89 

competent  to  pull  the  trigger  of  a  (symbolic)  nerve.  The 
physiologist  can  trace  the  nerve  mechanism  up  to  the 
brain;  but  ultimately  there  is  a  hiatus  which  no  one 
professes  to  fill  up.  Symbolically  we  may  follow  the 
influences  of  the  physical  world  up  to  the  door  of  the 
mind;  they  ring  the  door-bell  and  depart. 

But  the  association  of  "becoming"  with  entropy- 
change  is  not  to  be  understood  in  the  same  way.  It 
is  clearly  not  sufficient  that  the  change  in  the  random 
element  of  the  world  should  deliver  an  impulse  at  the 
end  of  a  nerve,  leaving  the  mind  to  create  in  response 
to  this  stimulus  the  fancy  that  it  is  turning  the  reel  of 
a  cinematograph.  Unless  we  have  been  altogether 
misreading  the  significance  of  the  world  outside  us — 
by  interpreting  it  in  terms  of  evolution  and  progress, 
instead  of  a  static  extension — we  must  regard  the 
feeling  of  "becoming"  as  (in  some  respects  at  least)  a 
true  mental  insight  into  the  physical  condition  which 
determines  it.  It  is  true  enough  that  whether  we  are 
dealing  with  the  experience  of  "becoming"  or  with  the 
more  typical  sense-experiences  of  light,  sound,  smell, 
etc.,  there  must  always  be  some  point  at  which  we  lose 
sight  of  the  physical  entities  ere  they  arise  in  new  dress 
above  our  mental  horizon.  But  if  there  is  any  experience 
in  which  this  mystery  of  mental  recognition  can  be 
interpreted  as  insight  rather  than  image-building,  it 
should  be  the  experience  of  "becoming";  because  in  this 
case  the  elaborate  nerve  mechanism  does  not  intervene. 
That  which  consciousness  is  reading  off  when  it  feels  the 
passing  moments  lies  just  outside  its  door.  Whereas, 
even  if  we  had  reason  to  regard  our  vivid  impression 
of  colour  as  insight,  it  could  not  be  insight  into  the 
electric  waves,  for  these  terminate  at  the  retina  far  from 
the  seat  of  consciousness. 


9o  "BECOMING" 

I  am  afraid  that  the  average  reader  will  feel  impa- 
tient with  the  long-winded  discussion  I  am  about  to  give 
concerning  the  dynamic  character  of  the  external  world. 
"What  is  all  the  bother  about?  Why  not  make  at  once 
the  hypothesis  that  'becoming'  is  a  kind  of  one-way 
texture  involved  fundamentally  in  the  structure  of 
Nature?  The  mind  is  cognisant  of  this  texture  (as  it  is 
cognisant  of  other  features  of  the  physical  world)  and 
apprehends  it  as  the  passing  on  of  time — a  fairly  correct 
appreciation  of  its  actual  nature.  As  a  result  of  this 
one-way  texture  the  random  element  increases  steadily 
in  the  direction  of  the  grain,  and  thus  conveniendy 
provides  the  physicist  with  an  experimental  criterion  for 
determining  the  way  of  the  grain;  but  it  is  the  grain 
and  not  this  particular  consequence  of  it  which  is  the 
direct  physical  counterpart  of  'becoming'.  It  may  be 
difficult  to  find  a  rigorous  proof  of  this  hypothesis;  but 
after  all  we  have  generally  to  be  content  with  hypotheses 
that  rest  only  on  plausibility." 

This  is  in  fact  the  kind  of  idea  which  I  wish  to 
advocate;  but  the  "average  reader"  has  probably  not 
appreciated  that  before  the  physicist  can  admit  it,  a 
delicate  situation  concerning  the  limits  of  scientific 
method  and  the  underlying  basis  of  physical  law  has  to 
be  faced.  It  is  one  thing  to  introduce  a  plausible 
hypothesis  in  order  to  explain  observational  phenomena; 
it  is  another  thing  to  introduce  it  in  order  to  give  the 
world  outside  us  a  significant  or  purposive  meaning, 
however  strongly  that  meaning  may  be  insisted  on  by 
something  in  our  conscious  nature.  From  the  side  of 
scientific  investigation  we  recognise  only  the  progressive 
change  in  the  random  element  from  the  end  of  the  world 
with  least  randomness  to  the  end  with  most;  that  in  itself 
gives  no  ground  for  suspecting  any  kind  of  dynamical 


ENTROPY  AND  BECOMING  91 

meaning.  The  view  here  advocated  is  tantamount  to  an 
admission  that  consciousness,  looking  out  through  a  pri- 
vate door,  can  learn  by  direct  insight  an  underlying  char- 
acter of  the  world  which  physical  measurements  do  not 
betray. 

In  any  attempt  to  bridge  the  domains  of  experience 
belonging  to  the  spiritual  and  physical  sides  of  our  na- 
ture, Time  occupies  the  key  position.  I  have  already  re- 
ferred to  its  dual  entry  into  our  consciousness — through 
the  sense  organs  which  relate  it  to  the  other  entities  of 
the  physical  world,  and  directly  through  a  kind  of  pri- 
vate door  into  the  mind.  The  physicist,  whose  method 
of  inquiry  depends  on  sharpening  up  our  sense  organs  by 
auxiliary  apparatus  of  precision,  naturally  does  not  look 
kindly  von  private  doors,  through  which  all  formsl  of 
superstitious  fancy  might  enter  unchecked.  But  is  he 
ready  to  forgo  that  knowledge  of  the  going  on  of  time 
which  has  reached  us  through  the  door,  and  content 
himself  with  the  time  inferred  from  sense-impressions 
which  is  emaciated  of  all  dynamic  quality? 

No  doubt  some  will  reply  that  they  are  content;  to 
these  I  would  say — Then  show  your  good  faith  by 
reversing  the  dynamic  quality  of  time  (which  you  may 
freely  do  if  it  has  no  importance  in  Nature),  and,  just 
for  a  change,  give  us  a  picture  of  the  universe  passing 
from  the  more  random  to  the  less  random  state,  each 
step  showing  a  gradual  victory  of  antichance  over 
chance.  If  you  are  a  biologist,  teach  us  how  from  Man 
and  a  myriad  other  primitive  forms  of  life,  Nature  in 
the  course  of  ages  achieved  the  sublimely  simple  struc- 
ture of  the  amoeba.  If  you  are  an  astronomer,  tell  how 
waves  of  light  hurry  in  from  the  depths  of  space  and 
condense  on  to  the  stars;  how  the  complex  solar  system 
unwinds  itself  into  the  evenness  of  a  nebula.     Is  this  the 


92  "BECOMING" 

enlightened  outlook  which  you  wish  to  substitute  for 
the  first  chapter  of  Genesis?  If  you  genuinely  believe 
that  a  contra-evolutionary  theory  is  just  as  true  and  as 
significant  as  an  evolutionary  theory,  surely  it  is  time  that 
a  protest  should  be  made  against  the  entirely  one-sided 
version  currently  taught. 


Dynamic  Quality  of  the  External  World.  But  for  our 
ulterior  conviction  of  the  dynamic  quality  of  time,  it 
would  be  possible  to  take  the  view  that  ''becoming"  is 
purely  subjective — that  there  is  no  "becoming"  in  the 
external  world  which  lies  passively  spread  out  in  the 
time-dimension  as  Minkowski  pictured  it.  My  con- 
sciousness then  invents  its  own  serial  order  for  the  sense 
impressions  belonging  to  the  different  view-points  along 
the  track  in  the  external  world,  occupied  by  the  four- 
dimensional  worm  who  is  in  some  mysterious  way 
Myself;  and  in  focussing  the  sensations  of  a  particular 
view-point  I  get  the  illusion  that  the  corresponding 
external  events  are  "taking  place".  I  suppose  that  this 
would  be  adequate  to  account  for  the  observed  phe- 
nomena. The  objections  to  it  hinge  on  the  fact  that  it 
leaves  the  external  world  without  any  dynamic  quality 
intrinsic  to  it. 

It  is  useful  to  recognise  how  some  of  our  most  ele- 
mentary reasoning  tacitly  assumes  the  existence  of  this 
dynamic  quality  or  trend;  to  eradicate  it  would  almost 
paralyse  our  faculties  of  inference.  In  the  operation  of 
shuffling  cards  it  seems  axiomatic  that  the  cards  must 
be  in  greater  disarrangement  at  a  later  instant.  Can 
you  conceive  Nature  to  be  such  that  this  is  not  obviously 
true?  But  what  do  we  here  mean  by  "later"?  So  far 
as  the  axiomatic  character  of  the  conclusion  is  concerned 


DYNAMIC  QUALITY  OF  THE  WORLD  93 

(not  its  experimental  verification)  we  cannot  mean 
"later"  as  judged  by  consciousness;  its  obviousness  is 
not  bound  up  with  any  speculations  as  to  the  behaviour 
of  consciousness.  Do  we  then  mean  "later"  as  judged 
by  the  physical  criterion  of  time's  arrow,  i.e.  corre- 
sponding to  a  greater  proportion  of  the  random  element? 
But  that  would  be  tautological — the  cards  are  more 
disarranged  when  there  is  more  of  the  random  element. 
We  did  not  mean  a  tautology;  we  unwittingly  accepted 
as  a  basis  for  our  thought  about  the  question  an  unam- 
biguous trend  from  past  to  future  in  the  space-time  where 
the  operation  of  shuffling  is  performed. 

The  crux  of  the  matter  is  that,  although  a  change 
described  as  sorting  is  the  exact  opposite  to  a  change 
described  as  shuffling  we  cannot  imagine  a  cause  of 
sorting  to  be  the  exact  opposite  of  a  cause  of  shuffling. 
Thus  a  reversal  of  the  time-direction  which  turns 
shuffling  into  sorting  does  not  make  the  appropriate 
transformation  of  their  causes.  Shuffling  can  have  in- 
organic causes,  but  sorting  is  the  prerogative  of  mind  or 
instinct.  We  cannot  believe  that  it  is  merely  an  orienta- 
tion with  respect  to  the  time-direction  which  differentiates 
us  from  inorganic  nature.  Shuffling  is  related  to  sorting 
(so  far  as  the  change  of  configuration  is  concerned)  as 
plus  is  to  minus;  but  to  say  that  the  cause  of  shuffling 
is  related  to  the  cause  of  sorting  in  the  same  way  would 
seem  equivalent  to  saying  that  the  activities  of  matter 
and  mind  are  related  like  plus  and  minus — which 
surely  is  nonsense.  Hence  if  we  view  the  world  from 
future  to  past  so  that  shuffling  and  sorting  are  inter- 
changed, their  causes  do  not  follow  suit,  and  the  rational 
connection  is  broken.  To  restore  coherency  we  must 
postulate  that  by  this  change  of  direction  something 
else  has  been  reversed,  viz.  the  trend  in  world-texture 


94  "BECOMING" 

spoken  of  above;  "becoming"  has  been  turned  into 
"unbecoming".  If  we  like  we  can  now  go  on  to  account, 
not  for  things  becoming  unshuffled,  but  for  their  un- 
becoming shuffled — and,  if  we  wish  to  pursue  this  aspect 
further,  we  must  discuss  not  the  causes  but  the  un- 
causes.  But,  without  tying  ourselves  into  verbal  knots, 
the  meaning  evidently  is  that  "becoming"  gives  a 
texture  to  the  world  which  it  is  illegitimate  to  reverse. 

Objectivity  of  Becoming.  In  general  we  should  describe 
the  familiar  world  as  subjective  and  the  scientific  world 
as  objective.  Take  for  instance  our  former  example  of 
parallelism,  viz.  colour  in  the  familiar  world  and  its 
counterpart  electromagnetic  wave-length  in  the  scientific 
world.  Here  we  have  little  hesitation  in  describing  the 
waves  as  objective  and  the  colour  as  subjective.  The 
wave  is  the  reality — or  the  nearest  we  can  get  to  a 
description  of  reality;  the  colour  is  mere  mind-spinning. 
The  beautiful  hues  which  flood  our  consciousness  under 
stimulation  of  the  waves  have  no  relevance  to  the  ob- 
jective reality.  For  a  colour-blind  person  the  hues  are 
different;  and  although  persons  of  normal  sight  make 
the  same  distinctions  of  colour,  we  cannot  ascertain 
whether  their  consciousness  of  red,  blue,  etc.  is  just  like 
our  own.  Moreover,  we  recognise  that  the  longer  and 
shorter  electromagnetic  waves  which  have  no  visual 
effect  associated  with  them  are  just  as  real  as  the  col- 
oured waves.  In  this  and  other  parallelisms  we  find  the 
objective  in  the  scientific  world  and  the  subjective  in  the 
familiar  world. 

But  in  the  parallelism  between  entropy-gradient  and 
"becoming"  the  subjective  and  objective  seem  to  have 
got  on  to  the  wrong  sides.  Surely  "becoming"  is  a 
reality — or  the  nearest  we  can  get  to  a  description  of 


OBJECTIVITY  OF  BECOMING  95 

reality.  We  are  convinced  that  a  dynamic  character 
must  be  attributed  to  the  external  world;  making  all 
allowance  for  mental  imagery,  I  do  not  see  how  the 
essence  of  "becoming"  can  be  much  different  from 
what  it  appears  to  us  to  be.  On  the  other  side  we  have 
entropy  which  is  frankly  of  a  much  more  subjective 
nature  than  most  of  the  ordinary  physical  qualities. 
Entropy  is  an  appreciation  of  arrangement  and  or- 
ganisation; it  is  subjective  in  the  same  sense  that  the 
constellation  Orion  is  subjective.  That  which  is  arranged 
is  objective,  so  too  are  the  stars  composing  the  con- 
stellation; but  the  association  is  the  contribution  of  the 
mind  which  surveys.  If  colour  is  mind-spinning,  so  also 
is  entropy  a  mind-spinning — of  the  statistician.  It  has 
about  as  much  objectivity  as   a  batting  average. 

Whilst  the  physicist  would  generally  say  that  the 
matter  of  this  familiar  table  is  really  a  curvature  of 
space,  and  its  colour  is  really  electromagnetic  wave- 
length, I  do  not  think  he  would  say  that  the  familiar 
moving  on  of  time  is  really  an  entropy-gradient.  I  am 
quoting  a  rather  loose  way  of  speaking;  but  it  reveals 
that  there  is  a  distinct  difference  in  our  attitude  towards 
the  last  parallelism.  Having  convinced  ourselves  that 
the  two  things  are  connected,  we  must  conclude  that 
there  is  something  as  yet  ungrasped  behind  the  notion 
of  entropy — some  mystic  interpretation,  if  you  like — 
which  is  not  apparent  in  the  definition  by  which  we 
introduced  it  into  physics.  "  In  short  we  strive  to  see 
that  entropy-gradient  may  really  be  the  moving  on  of 
time  (instead  of  vice  versa). 

Before  passing  on  I  would  note  that  this  exceptional 
appearance  of  subjective  and  objective  apparently  in 
their  wrong  worlds  gives  food  for  thought.  It  may 
prepare  us  for  a  view  of  the  scientific  world  adopted  in 


96  "BECOMING" 

the  later  chapters  which  is  much  more  subjective  than 
that  usually  held  by  science. 

The  more  closely  we  examine  the  association  of 
entropy  with  "becoming"  the  greater  do  the  obstacles 
appear.  If  entropy  were  one  of  the  elementary  in- 
definables  of  physics  there  would  be  no  difficulty.  Or 
if  the  moving  on  of  time  were  something  of  which  we 
were  made  aware  through  our  sense  organs  there  would 
be  no  difficulty.  But  the  actual  combination  which  we 
have  to  face  seems  to  be  unique  in  its  difficulty. 

Suppose  that  we  had  had  to  identify  "becoming" 
with  electrical  potential-gradient  instead  of  with  en- 
tropy-change. We  discover  potential  through  the 
readings  of  a  voltmeter.  The  numerical  reading  stands 
for  something  in  the  condition  of  the  world,  but  we  form 
no  picture  of  what  that  something  is.  In  scientific 
researches  we  only  make  use  of  the  numerical  value — 
a  code-number  attached  to  a  background  outside  all 
conception.  It  would  be  very  interesting  if  we  could 
relate  this  mysterious  potential  to  any  of  our  familiar 
conceptions.  Clearly,  if  we  could  identify  the  change 
of  potential  with  the  familiar  moving  on  of  time,  we 
should  have  made  a  great  step  towards  grasping  its 
intrinsic  nature.  But  turning  from  supposition  to  fact, 
we  have  to  identify  potential-gradient  with  force.  Now 
it  is  true  that  we  have  a  familiar  conception  of  force — 
a  sensation  of  muscular  effort.  But  this  does  not  give 
us  any  idea  of  the  intrinsic  nature  of  potential-gradient; 
the  sensation  is  mere  mind-spinning  provoked  by 
nervous  impulses  which  have  travelled  a  long  way  from 
the  seat  of  the  force.  That  is  the  way  with  all  physical 
entities  which  affect  the  mind  through  the  sense  organs. 
The  interposed  nerve-mechanism  would  prevent  any  close 
association  of  the  mental  image  with  the  physical  cause, 


OBJECTIVITY  OF  BECOMING  97 

even  if  we  were  disposed  to  trust  our  mental  insight  when 
it  has  a  chance  of  operating  directly. 

Or  suppose  that  we  had  had  to  identify  force  with 
entropy-gradient.  That  would  only  mean  that  entropy- 
gradient  is  a  condition  which  stimulates  a  nerve,  which 
thereupon  transmits  an  impulse  to  the  brain,  out  of 
which  the  mind  weaves  its  own  peculiar  impression  of 
force.  No  one  would  feel  intuitive  objection  to  the 
hypothesis  that  the  muscular  sensation  of  force  is 
associated  with  change  of  organisation  of  the  molecules 
of  the  muscle. 

Our  trouble  is  that  we  have  to  associate  two  things, 
both  of  which  we  more  or  less  understand,  and,  so  far 
as  we  understand  them,  they  are  utterly  different.  It 
is  absurd  to  pretend  that  we  are  in  ignorance  of  the 
nature  of  organisation  in  the  external  world  in  the  same 
way  that  we  are  ignorant  of  the  intrinsic  nature  of 
potential.  It  is  absurd  to  pretend  that  we  have  no 
justifiable  conception  of  "becoming"  in  the  external 
world.  That  dynamic  quality — that  significance  which 
makes  a  development  from  past  to  future  reasonable 
and  a  development  from  future  to  past  farcical — has  to 
do  much  more  than  pull  the  trigger  of  a  nerve.  It  is  so 
welded  into  our  consciousness  that  a  moving  on  of 
time  is  a  condition  of  consciousness.  We  have  direct 
insight  into  "becoming"  which  sweeps  aside  all  sym- 
bolic knowledge  as  on  an  inferior  plane.  If  I  grasp  the 
notion  of  existence  because  I  myself  exist,  I  grasp  the  no- 
tion of  becoming  because  I  myself  become.  It  is  the  in- 
nermost Ego  of  all  which  is  and  becomes. 

The  incongruity  of  symbolising  this  fundamental 
intuition  by  a  property  of  arrangement  of  the  micro- 
scopic constituents  of  the  world,  is  evident.  What  this 
difficulty  portends  is  still  very  obscure.     But  it  is  not 


98  "BECOMING" 

irrelevant  to  certain  signs  of  change  which  we  may 
discern  in  responsible  scientific  opinion  with  regard  to 
the  question  of  primary  and  secondary  law.  The  cast- 
iron  determinism  of  primary  law  is,  I  think,  still  widely 
accepted  but  no  longer  unquestioningly.  It  now  seems 
clear  that  we  have  not  yet  got  hold  of  any  primary  law 
— that  all  those  laws  at  one  time  supposed  to  be  primary 
are  in  reality  statistical.  No  doubt  it  will  be  said  that 
that  was  only  to  be  expected;  we  must  be  prepared  for 
a  very  long  search  before  we  get  down  to  ultimate 
foundations,  and  not  be  disappointed  if  new  discoveries 
reveal  unsuspected  depths  beneath.  But  I  think  it  might 
be  said  that  Nature  has  been  caught  using  rather  unfair 
dodges  to  prevent  our  discovering  primary  law — that 
kind  of  artfulness  which  frustrated  our  efforts  to  discover 
velocity  relative  to  the  aether.*  I  believe  that  Nature  is 
honest  at  heart,  and  that  she  only  resorts  to  these  ap- 
parent shifts  of  concealment  when  we  are  looking  for 
something  which  is  not  there.  It  is  difficult  to  see  now 
any  justification  for  the  strongly  rooted  conviction  in  the 
ultimate  re-establishment  of  a  deterministic  scheme  of 
law  except  a  supposed  necessity  of  thought.  Thought 
has  grown  accustomed  to  doing  without  a  great  many 
"necessities"  in  recent  years. 

One  would  not  be  surprised  if  in  the  reconstruction 
of  the  scheme  of  physics  which  the  quantum  theory  is 
now  pressing  on  us,  secondary  law  becomes  the  basis 
and  primary  law  is  discarded.  In  the  reconstructed 
world  nothing  is  impossible  though  many  things  are 
improbable.  The  effect  is  much  the  same,  but  the  kind 
of  machinery  that  we  must  conceive  is  altogether 
different.  We  shall  have  further  glimpses  of  this  problem 
and  I  will  not  here  pursue  it.     Entropy,  being  a  quantity 

*  See  p.  23i. 


OUR  DUAL  RECOGNITION  OF  TIME  99 

introduced  in  connection  with  secondary  law  will  now 
exist,  so  to  speak,  in  its  own  right  instead  of  by  its 
current  representation  as  arrangement  of  the  quantities 
in  the  abandoned  primary  scheme;  and  in  that  right  it 
may  be  more  easily  accepted  as  the  symbol  for  the 
dynamic  quality  of  the  world.  I  cannot  make  my 
meaning  more  precise,  because  I  am  speaking  of  a 
still  hypothetical  change  of  ideas  which  no  one  has  been 
able  to  bring  about. 

Our  Dual  Recognition  of  Time,  Another  curiosity  which 
strikes  us  is  the  divorce  in  physics  between  time  and 
time's  arrow.  A  being  from  another  world  who  wishes 
to  discover  the  temporal  relation  of  two  events  in  this 
world  has  to  read  two  different  indicators.  He  must 
read  a  clock  in  order  to  find  out  how  much  later  one 
event  is  than  the  other,  and  he  must  read  some  arrange- 
ment for  measuring  the  disorganisation  of  energy  (e.g.  a 
thermometer)  in  order  to  discover  which  event  is  the 
later.*  The  division  of  labour  is  especially  striking 
when  we  remember  that  our  best  clocks  are  those  in 
which  all  processes  such  as  friction,  which  introduce 
disorganisation  of  energy,  are  eliminated  as  far  as 
possible.  The  more  perfect  the  instrument  as  a  meas- 
urer of  time,  the  more  completely  does  it  conceal  time's 
arrow. 


*  To  make  the  test  strictly  from  another  world  he  must  not  assume 
that  the  figures  marked  on  the  clock-dial  necessarily  go  the  right  way 
round;  nor  must  he  assume  that  the  progress  of  his  consciousness  has 
any  relation  to  the  flow  of  time  in  our  world.  He  has,  therefore,  merely 
two  dial-readings  for  the  two  events  without  knowing  whether  the 
difference  should  be  reckoned  plus  or  minus.  The  thermometer  would 
be  used  in  conjunction  with  a  hot  and  cold  body  in  contact.  The  differ- 
ence of  the  thermometer  readings  for  the  two  bodies  would  be  taken  at 
the  moment  of  each  event.  The  event  for  which  the  difference  is  smaller 
is  the  later. 


ioo  "BECOMING" 

This  paradox  seems  to  be  explained  by  the  fact 
pointed  out  in  chapter  in  that  time  comes  into  our 
consciousness  by  two  routes.  We  picture  the  mind  like 
an  editor  in  his  sanctum  receiving  through  the  nerves 
scrappy  messages  from  all  over  the  outside  world,  and 
making  a  story  of  them  with,  I  fear,  a  good  deal  of 
editorial  invention.  Like  other  physical  quantities  time 
enters  in  that  way  as  a  particular  measurable  relation 
between  events  in  the  outside  world;  but  it  comes  in 
without  its  arrow.  In  addition  our  editor  himself  ex- 
periences a  time  in  his  consciousness — the  temporal 
relation  along  his  own  track  through  the  world.  This 
experience  is  immediate,  not  a  message  from  outside, 
but  the  editor  realises  that  what  he  is  experiencing  is 
equivalent  to  the  time  described  in  the  messages.  Now 
consciousness  declares  that  this  private  time  possesses 
an  arrow,  and  so  gives  a  hint  to  search  further  for  the 
missing  arrow  among  the  messages.  The  curious  thing 
is  that,  although  the  arrow  is  ultimately  found  among 
the  messages  from  outside,  it  is  not  found  in  the  mes- 
sages from  clocks,  but  in  messages  from  thermometers 
and  the  like  instruments  which  do  not  ordinarily  pretend 
to  measure  time. 

Consciousness,  besides  detecting  time's  arrow,  also 
roughly  measures  the  passage  of  time.  It  has  the  right 
idea  of  time-measurement,  but  is  a  bit  of  a  bungler  in 
carrying  it  out.  Our  consciousness  somehow  manages 
to  keep  in  close  touch  with  the  material  world,  and  we 
must  suppose  that  its  record  of  the  flight  of  time  is  the 
reading  of  some  kind  of  a  clock  in  the  material  of  the 
brain — possibly  a  clock  which  is  a  rather  bad  time- 
keeper. I  have  generally  had  in  mind  in  this  connection 
an  analogy  with  the  clocks  of  physics  designed  for  good 
time-keeping;   but   I    am  now   inclined   to   think   that   a 


OUR  DUAL  RECOGNITION  OF  TIME         101 

better  analogy  would  be  an  entropy-clock,  i.e.  an  in- 
strument designed  primarily  for  measuring  the  rate  of 
disorganisation  of  energy,  and  only  very  roughly  keep- 
ing pace  with  time. 

A  typical  entropy-clock  might  be  designed  as  follows. 
An  electric  circuit  is  composed  of  two  different  metals 
with  their  two  junctions  embedded  respectively  in  a 
hot  and  cold  body  in  contact.  The  circuit  contains  a 
galvanometer  which  constitutes  the  dial  of  the  entropy- 
clock.  The  thermoelectric  current  in  the  circuit  is 
proportional  to  the  difference  of  temperature  of  the  two 
bodies;  so  that  as  the  shuffling  of  energy  between  them 
proceeds,  the  temperature  difference  decreases  and  the 
galvanometer  reading  continually  decreases.  This  clock 
will  infallibly  tell  an  observer  from  another  world  which 
of  two  events  is  the  later.  We  have  seen  that  no  ordi- 
nary clock  can  do  this.  As  to  its  time-keeping  qualities 
we  can  only  say  that  the  motion  of  the  galvanometer 
needle  has  some  connection  with  the  rate  of  passage  of 
time — which  is  perhaps  as  much  as  can  be  said  for  the 
time-keeping  qualities  of  consciousness. 

It  seems  to  me,  therefore,  that  consciousness  with  its 
insistence  on  time's  arrow  and  its  rather  erratic  ideas  of 
time  measurement  may  be  guided  by  entropy-clocks  in 
some  portion  of  the  brain.  That  avoids  the  unnatural 
assumption  that  we  consult  two  different  cells  of  the 
material  brain  in  forming  our  ideas  of  duration  and  of 
becoming,  respectively.  Entropy-gradient  is  then  the 
direct  equivalent  of  the  time  of  consciousness  in  both 
its  aspects.  Duration  measured  by  physical  clocks  (time- 
like interval)  is  only  remotely  connected. 

Let  us  try  to  clear  up  our  ideas  of  time  by  a  summary 
of  the  position  now  reached.     Firstly,  physical  time  is  a 


102  "BECOMING" 

system  of  partitions  in  the  four-dimensional  world 
(world-wide  instants).  These  are  artificial  and  relative 
and  by  no  means  correspond  to  anything  indicated  to 
us  by  the  time  of  consciousness.  Secondly,  we  recognise 
in  the  relativity  theory  something  called  a  temporal 
relation  which  is  absolutely  distinct  from  a  spatial 
relation.  One  consequence  of  this  distinction  is  that  the 
mind  attached  to  a  material  body  can  only  traverse  a 
temporal  relation;  so  that,  even  if  there  is  no  closer 
connection,  there  is  at  least  a  one-to-one  correspondence 
between  the  sequence  of  phases  of  the  mind  and  a 
sequence  of  points  in  temporal  relation.  Since  the  mind 
interprets  its  own  sequence  as  a  time  of  consciousness,  we 
can  at  least  say  that  the  temporal  relation  in  physics 
has  a  connection  with  the  time  of  consciousness  which 
the  spatial  relation  does  not  possess.  I  doubt  if  the 
connection  is  any  closer.  I  do  not  think  the  mental 
sequence  is  a  "reading  off"  of  the  physical  temporal 
relation,  because  in  physics  the  temporal  relation  is 
arrowless.  I  think  it  is  a  reading  off  of  the  physical 
entropy-gradient,  since  this  has  the  necessary  arrow. 
Temporal  relation  and  entropy-gradient,  both  rigorously 
defined  in  physics,  are  entirely  distinct  and  in  general 
are  not  numerically  related.  But,  of  course,  other  things 
besides  time  can  "keep  time";  and  there  is  no  reason 
why  the  generation  of  the  random  element  in  a  special 
locality  of  the  brain  should  not  proceed  fairly  uniformly. 
In  that  case  there  will  not  be  too  great  a  divergence 
between  the  passage  of  time  in  consciousness  and  the 
length  of  the  corresponding  temporal  relation  in  the 
physical  world. 


THE  REACTION  FROM  ANALYSIS  103 

The  Scientific  Reaction  from  Microscopic  Analysis.  From 
the  point  of  view  of  philosophy  of  science  the  con- 
ception associated  with  entropy  must  I  think  be  ranked 
as  the  great  contribution  of  the  nineteenth  century  to 
scientific  thought.  It  marked  a  reaction  from  the  view 
that  everything  to  which  science  need  pay  attention  is 
discovered  by  a  microscopic  dissection  of  objects.  It 
provided  an  alternative  standpoint  in  which  the  centre 
of  interest  is  shifted  from  the  entities  reached  by  the 
customary  analysis  (atoms,  electric  potentials,  etc.)  to 
qualities  possessed  by  the  system  as  a  whole,  which 
cannot  be  split  up  and  located — a  little  bit  here,  and  a 
little  bit  there.  The  artist  desires  to  convey  significances 
which  cannot  be  told  by  microscopic  detail  and  accord- 
ingly he  resorts  to  impressionist  painting.  Strangely 
enough  the  physicist  has  found  the  same  necessity;  but 
his  impressionist  scheme  is  just  as  much  exact  science 
and  even  more  practical  in  its  application  than  his  micro- 
scopic  scheme. 

Thus  in  the  study  of  the  falling  stone  the  microscopic 
analysis  reveals  myriads  of  separate  molecules.  The 
energy  of  the  stone  is  distributed  among  the  molecules, 
the  sum  of  the  energies  of  the  molecules  making  up  the 
energy  of  the  stone.  But  we  cannot  distribute  in  that 
way  the  organisation  or  the  random  element  in  the 
motions.  It  would  be  meaningless  to  say  that  a  particu- 
lar fraction  of  the  organisation  is  located  in  a  par- 
ticular molecule. 

There  is  one  ideal  of  survey  which  would  look  into 
each  minute  compartment  of  space  in  turn  to  see  what 
it  may  contain  and  so  make  what  it  would  regard  as 
a  complete  inventory  of  the  world.  But  this  misses 
any  world-features  which  are  not  located  in  minute 
compartments.      We    often    think    that   when    we   have 


104  "BECOMING" 

completed  our  study  of  one  we  know  all  about  two>  be- 
cause "two"  is  "one  and  one".  We  forget  that  we  have 
still  to  make  a  study  of  "and".  Secondary  physics  is 
the  study  of  "and" — that  is  to  say,  of  organisation. 

Thanks  to  clear-sighted  pioneers  in  the  last  century 
science  became  aware  that  it  was  missing  something  of 
practical  importance  by  following  the  inventory  method 
of  the  primary  scheme  of  physics.  Entropy  became 
recognised  although  it  was  not  found  in  any  of  the  com- 
partments. It  was  discovered  and  exalted  because  it  was 
essential  to  practical  applications  of  physics,  not  to 
satisfy  any  philosophic  hungering.  But  by  it  science 
has  been  saved  from  a  fatal  narrowness.  If  we  had  kept 
entirely  to  the  inventory  method,  there  would  have  been 
nothing  to  represent  "becoming"  in  the  physical  world. 
And  science,  having  searched  high  and  low,  would 
doubtless  have  reported  that  "becoming"  is  an  un- 
founded mental  illusion — like  beauty,  life,  the  soul,  and 
other  things  which  it  is  unable  to  inventory. 

I  think  that  doubts  might  well  have  been  entertained 
as  to  whether  the  newcomer  was  strictly  scientific. 
Entropy  was  not  in  the  same  category  as  the  other 
physical  quantities  recognised  in  science,  and  the  ex- 
tension— as  we  shall  presently  see — was  in  a  very 
dangerous  direction.  Once  you  admit  attributes  of 
arrangement  as  subject-matter  of  physics,  it  is  difficult 
to  draw  the  line.  But  entropy  had  secured  a  firm  place 
in  physics  before  it  was  discovered  that  it  was  a  measure 
of  the  random  element  in  arrangement.  It  was  in  great 
favour  with  the  engineers.  Their  sponsorship  was  the 
highest  testimonial  to  its  good  character;  because  at  that 
time  it  was  the  general  assumption  that  the  Creation  was 
the  work  of  an  engineer  (not  of  a  mathematician,  as  is 
the  fashion  nowadays). 


THE  REACTION  FROM  ANALYSIS  105 

Suppose  that  we  were  asked  to  arrange  the  following 
in  two  categories — 

distance,  mass,  electric  force,  entropy,  beauty,  melody. 

I  think  there  are  the  strongest  grounds  for  placing 
entropy  alongside  beauty  and  melody  and  not  with  the 
first  three.  Entropy  is  only  found  when  the  parts  are 
viewed  in  association,  and  it  is  by  viewing  or  hearing 
the  parts  in  association  that  beauty  and  melody  are 
discerned.  All  three  are  features  of  arrangement.  It  is 
a  pregnant  thought  that  one  of  these  three  associates 
should  be  able  to  figure  as  a  commonplace  quantity  of 
science.  The  reason  why  this  stranger  can  pass  itself 
off  among  the  aborigines  of  the  physical  world  is,  that 
it  is  able  to  speak  their  language,  viz.  the  language  of 
arithmetic.  It  has  a  measure-number  associated  with  it 
and  so  is  made  quite  at  home  in  physics.  Beauty  and 
melody  have  not  the  arithmetical  pass-word  and  so  are 
barred  out.  This  teaches  us  that  what  exact  science  looks 
out  for  is  not  entities  of  some  particular  category,  but 
entities  with  a  metrical  aspect.  We  shall  see  in  a  later 
chapter  that  when  science  admits  them  it  really  admits 
only  their  metrical  aspect  and  occupies  itself  solely  with 
that.  It  would  be  no  use  for  beauty,  say,  to  fake  up  a 
few  numerical  attributes  (expressing  for  instance  the 
ideal  proportions  of  symmetry)  in  the  hope  of  thereby 
gaining  admission  into  the  portals  of  science  and  carrying 
on  an  aesthetic  crusade  within.  It  would  find  that  the 
numerical  aspects  were  duly  admitted,  but  the  aesthetic 
significance  of  them  left  outside.  So  also  entropy  is 
admitted  in  its  numerical  aspect;  if  it  has  as  we  faintly 
suspect  some  deeper  significance  touching  that  which 
appears  in  our  consciousness  as  purpose  (opposed  to 
chance) ,  that  significance  is  left  outside.     These  fare  no 


106  "BECOMING" 

worse  than  mass,  distance,  and  the  like  which  surely 
must  have  some  significance  beyond  mere  numbers;  if 
so,  that  significance  is  lost  on  their  incorporation  into 
the  scientific  scheme — the  world  of  shadows. 

You  may  be  inclined  to  regard  my  insistence  that 
entropy  is  something  excluded  from  the  inventory  of 
microscopic  contents  of  the  world  as  word-splitting.  If 
you  have  all  the  individuals  before  you,  their  associations, 
arrangement  and  organisation  are  automatically  before 
you.  If  you  have  the  stars,  you  have  the  constellations. 
Yes;  but  if  you  have  the  stars,  you  do  not  take  the 
constellations  seriously.  It  had  become  the  regular 
outlook  of  science,  closely  associated  with  its  materialistic 
tendencies,  that  constellations  are  not  to  be  taken 
seriously,  until  the  constellation  of  entropy  made  a 
solitary  exception.  When  we  analyse  the  picture  into 
a  large  number  of  particles  of  paint,  we  lose  the  aes- 
thetic significance  of  the  picture.  The  particles  of  paint 
go  into  the  scientific  inventory,  and  it  is  claimed  that 
everything  that  there  really  was  in  the  picture  is  kept. 
But  this  way  of  keeping  a  thing  may  be  much  the  same 
as  losing  it.  The  essence  of  a  picture  (as  distinct  from 
the  paint)  is  arrangement.  Is  arrangement  kept  or  lost? 
The  current  answer  seems  inconsistent.  In  so  far  as 
arrangement  signifies  a  picture,  it  is  lost;  science  has 
to  do  with  paint,  not  pictures.  In  so  far  as  arrangement 
signifies  organisation  it  is  kept;  science  has  much  to  do 
with  organisation.  Why  should  we  (speaking  now  as 
philosophers,  not  scientists)  make  a  discrimination 
between  these  two  aspects  of  arrangement?  The  dis- 
crimination is  made  because  the  picture  is  no  use  to  the 
scientist — he  cannot  get  further  with  it.  As  impartial 
judges  it  is  our  duty  to  point  out  that  likewise  entropy 
is  no  use  to  the  artist — he  cannot  develop  his  outlook 
with  it. 


INSUFFICIENCY  OF  PRIMARY  LAW  107 

I  am  not  trying  to  argue  that  there  is  in  the  external 
world  an  objective  entity  which  is  the  picture  as  distinct 
from  the  myriads  of  particles  into  which  science  has 
analysed  it.  I  doubt  if  the  statement  has  any  meaning; 
nor,  if  it  were  true,  would  it  particularly  enhance  my 
esteem  of  the  picture.  What  I  would  say  is  this: 
There  is  a  side  of  our  personality  which  impels  us  to 
dwell  on  beauty  and  other  aesthetic  significances  in 
Nature,  and  in  the  work  of  man,  so  that  our  environ- 
ment means  to  us  much  that  is  not  warranted  by  any- 
thing found  in  the  scientific  inventory  of  its  struc- 
ture. An  overwhelming  feeling  tells  us  that  this  is 
right  and  indispensable  to  the  purpose  of  our  existence. 
But  is  it  rational?  How  can  reason  regard  it  otherwise 
than  as  a  perverse  misrepresentation  of  what  is  after  all 
only  a  collection  of  atoms,  aether-waves  and  the  like, 
going  about  their  business?  If  the  physicist  as  advocate 
for  reason  takes  this  line,  just  whisper  to  him  the  word 
Entropy. 

Insufficiency  of  Primary  Law.  I  daresay  many  of  my 
physical  colleagues  will  join  issue  with  me  over  the 
status  I  have  allowed  to  entropy  as  something  foreign 
to  the  microscopic  scheme,  but  essential  to  the  physical 
world.  They  would  regard  it  rather  as  a  labour-saving 
device,  useful  but  not  indispensable.  Given  any  practical 
problem  ordinarily  solved  by  introducing  the  conception 
of  entropy,  precisely  the  same  result  could  be  reached 
(more  laboriously)  by  following  out  the  motion  of  each 
individual  particle  of  matter  or  quantum  of  energy  under 
the  primary  microscopic  laws  without  any  reference  to 
entropy  explicit  or  implicit.  Very  well ;  let  us  try.  There's 
a  problem  for  you — 

[A  piece  of  chalk  was  thrown  on  the  lecture  table 
where  it  rolled  and  broke  into  two  pieces.] 


108  "BECOMING" 

You  are  given  the  instantaneous  position  and  velocity* 
of  every  molecule,  or  if  you  like  every  proton  and 
electron,  in  those  pieces  of  chalk  and  in  as  much  of  the 
table  and  surrounding  air  as  concerns  you.  Details  of 
the  instantaneous  state  of  every  element  of  energy  are 
also  given.  By  the  microscopic  (primary)  laws  of  mo- 
tion you  can  trace  the  state  from  instant  to  instant. 
You  can  trace  how  the  atoms  moving  aimlessly  within 
the  lumps  of  chalk  gradually  form  a  conspiracy  so  that 
the  lumps  begin  to  move  as  a  whole.  The  lumps  bounce 
a  little  and  roll  on  the  table;  they  come  together  and 
join  up;  then  the  whole  piece  of  chalk  rises  gracefully 
in  the  air,  describes  a  parabola,  and  comes  to  rest  be- 
tween my  fingers.  I  grant  that  you  can  do  all  that  with- 
out requiring  entropy  or  anything  outside  the  limits  of 
microscopic  physics.  You  have  solved  the  problem. 
But,  have  you  quite  got  hold  of  the  significance  of  your 
solution?  Is  it  quite  a  negligible  point  that  what  you 
have  described  from  your  calculations  is  an  unhappen- 
ingf  There  is  no  need  to  alter  a  word  of  your  descrip- 
tion so  far  as  it  goes;  but  it  does  seem  to  need  an 
addendum  which  would  discriminate  between  a  trick 
worthy  of  Mr.  Maskelyne  and  an  ordinary  everyday 
unoccurrence. 

The  physicist  may  say  that  the  addendum  asked  for 
relates  to  significance,  and  he  has  nothing  to  do  with 
significances;  he  is  only  concerned  that  his  calculations 
shall  agree  with  observation.  He  cannot  tell  me  whether 
the  phenomenon  has  the  significance  of  a  happening  or 
an    unhappening;    but    if    a    clock    is    included    in    the 

*  Velocities  are  relative  to  a  frame  of  space  and  time.  Indicate  which 
frame  you  prefer,  and  you  will  be  given  velocity  relative  to  that  frame. 
(This  throws  on  you  the  responsibility  for  any  labelling  of  the  frame — 
left,  right,  past  future*  etc.) 


INSUFFICIENCY  OF  PRIMARY  LAW  109 

problem  he  can  give  the  readings  of  the  clock  at  each 
stage.  There  is  much  to  be  said  for  excluding  the  whole 
field  of  significance  from  physics;  it  is  a  healthy  reaction 
against  mixing  up  with  our  calculations  mystic  con- 
ceptions that  (officially)  we  know  nothing  about. 
I  rather  envy  the  pure  physicist  his  impregnable  position. 
But  if  he  rules  significances  entirely  outside  his  scope, 
somebody  has  the  job  of  discovering  whether  the  physi- 
cal world  of  atoms,  aether  and  electrons  has  any  signifi- 
cance whatever.  Unfortunately  for  me  I  am  expected  in 
these  lectures  to  say  how  the  plain  man  ought  to  regard 
the  scientific  world  when  it  comes  into  competition  with 
other  views  of  our  environment.  Some  of  my  audience 
may  not  be  interested  in  a  world  invented  as  a  mere 
calculating  device.  Am  I  to  tell  them  that  the  scientific 
world  has  no  claim  on  their  consideration  when  the  eter- 
nal question  surges  in  the  mind,  What  is  it  all  about?  I 
am  sure  my  physical  colleagues  will  expect  me  to  put  up 
some  defence  of  the  scientific  world  in  this  connection. 
I  am  ready  to  do  so;  only  I  must  insist  as  a  preliminary 
that  we  should  settle  which  is  the  right  way  up  of  it. 
I  cannot  read  any  significance  into  a  physical  world 
when  it  is  held  before  me  upside  down,  as  happened 
just  now.  For  that  reason  I  am  interested  in  entropy 
not  only  because  it  shortens  calculations  which  can  be 
made  by  other  methods,  but  because  it  determines  an 
orientation  which  cannot  be   found  by  other  methods. 

The  scientific  world  is,  as  I  have  often  repeated,  a 
shadow-world,  shadowing  a  world  familiar  to  our  con- 
sciousness. Just  how  much  do  we  expect  it  to  shadow? 
We  do  not  expect  it  to  shadow  all  that  is  in  our  mind, 
emotions,  memory,  etc.  In  the  main  we  expect  it  to 
shadow  impressions  which  can  be  traced  to  external 
sense-organs.      But  time   makes   a  dual   entry   and  thus 


no  "BECOMING" 

t 

forms  an  intermediate  link  between  the  internal  and  the 
external.  This  is  shadowed  partially  by  the  scientific 
world  of  primary  physics  (which  excludes  time's  ar- 
row), but  fully  when  we  enlarge  the  scheme  to  include 
entropy.  Therefore  by  the  momentous  departure  in  the 
nineteenth  century  the  scientific  world  is  not  confined  to 
a  static  extension  around  which  the  mind  may  spin  a 
romance  of  activity  and  evolution;  it  shadows  that 
dynamic  quality  of  the  familiar  world  which  cannot  be 
parted  from  it  without  disaster  to  its  significance. 

In  sorting  out  the  confused  data  of  our  experience  it 
has  generally  been  assumed  that  the  object  of  the  quest 
is  to  find  out  all  that  really  exists.  There  is  another 
quest  not  less  appropriate  to  the  nature  of  our  experience 
— to  find  out  all  that  really  becomes. 


Chapter  VI 
GRAVITATION— THE  LAW 

You  sometimes  speak  of  gravity  as  essential  and  inherent  to  matter.  Pray 
do  not  ascribe  that  notion  to  me;  for  the  cause  of  gravity  is  what  I  do  not 
pretend  to  know,  and  therefore  would  take  more  time  to  consider  of 
it.  .    .    . 

Gravity  must  be  caused  by  some  agent  acting  constantly  according 
to  certain  laws;  but  whether  this  agent  be  material  or  immaterial  I  have 
left  to  the  consideration  of  my  readers. 

Newton,  Letters  to  Bentley. 

The  Man  in  the  Lift.  About  19 15  Einstein  made  a 
further  development  of  his  theory  of  relativity  extending 
it  to  non-uniform  motion.  The  easiest  way  to  approach 
this  subject  is  by  considering  the  Man  in  the  Lift. 

Suppose  that  this  room  is  a  lift.  The  support  breaks 
and  down  we  go  with  ever-increasing  velocity,  falling 
freely. 

Let  us  pass  the  time  by  performing  physical  experi- 
ments. The  lift  is  our  laboratory  and  we  shall  start  at 
the  beginning  and  try  to  discover  all  the  laws  of  Nature 
— that  is  to  say,  Nature  as  interpreted  by  the  Man  in 
the  Lift.  To  a  considerable  extent  this  will  be  a  repeti- 
tion of  the  history  of  scientific  discovery  already  made 
in  the  laboratories  on  terra  firma.  But  there  is  one 
notable  difference. 

I  perform  the  experiment  of  dropping  an  apple  held 
in  the  hand.  The  apple  cannot  fall  any  more  than  it 
was  doing  already.  You  remember  that  our  lift  and  all 
things  contained  in  it  are  falling  freely.  Consequently 
the  apple  remains  poised 'by  my  hand.  There  is  one 
incident  in  the  history  of  science  which  will  not  repeat 
itself  to  the  men  in  the  lift,  viz.  Newton  and  the  apple 
tree.     The  magnificent  conception  that  the  agent  which 

in 


ii2  GRAVITATION— THE  LAW 

guides  the  stars  in  their  courses  is  the  same  as  that 
which  in  our  common  experience  causes  apples  to  drop, 
breaks  down  because  it  is  our  common  experience  in  the 
lift  that  apples  do  not  drop. 

I  think  we  have  now  sufficient  evidence  to  prove  that 
in  all  other  respects  the  scientific  laws  determined  in 
the  lift  will  agree  with  those  determined  under  more 
orthodox  conditions.  But  for  this  one  omission  the  men 
in  the  lift  will  derive  all  the  laws  of  Nature  with  which 
wre  are  acquainted,  and  derive  them  in  the  same  form 
that  we  have  derived  them.  Only  the  force  which 
causes  apples  to  fall  is  not  present  in  their  scheme. 

I  am  crediting  our  observers  in  the  lift  with  the  usuai 
egocentric  attitude,  viz.  the  aspect  of  the  world  to  me 
is  its  natural  one.  It  does  not  strike  them  as  odd  to 
spend  their  lives  falling  in  a  lift;  they  think  it  much 
more  odd  to  be  perched  on  the  earth's  surface.  There- 
fore although  they  perhaps  have  calculated  that  to  beings 
supported  in  this  strange  way  apples  would  seem  to 
have  a  perplexing  habit  of  falling,  they  do  not  take  our 
experience  of  the  ways  of  apples  any  more  seriously 
than  we  have  hitherto  taken  theirs. 

Are  we  to  take  their  experience  seriously?  Or  to  put 
it  another  way — What  is  the  comparative  importance  to 
be  attached  to  a  scheme  of  natural  laws  worked  out  by 
observers  in  the  falling  lift  and  one  worked  out  by 
observers  on  terra  ftrmal  Is  one  truer  than  the  other? 
Is  one  superior  to  the  other?  Clearly  the  difference  if 
any  arises  from  the  fact  that  the  schemes  are  referred 
to  different  frames  of  space  and  time.  Our  frame  is  a 
frame  in  which  the  solid  ground  is  at  rest;  similarly  their 
frame  is  a  frame  in  which  their  lift  is  at  rest.  We  have 
had  examples  before  of  observers  using  different  frames, 
but  those   frames  differed  by  a  uniform  velocity.     The 


THE  MAN  IN  THE  LIFT  113 

velocity  of  the  lift  is  ever-increasing — accelerated.  Can 
we  extend  to  accelerated  frames  our  principle  that 
Nature  is  indifferent  to  frames  of  space  and  time,  so 
that  no  one  frame  is  superior  to  any  other?  I  think  we 
can.  The  only  doubt  that  arises  is  whether  we  should 
not  regard  the  frame  of  the  man  in  the  lift  as  superior 
to,  instead  of  being  merely  coequal  with,  our  usual 
frame. 

When  we  stand  on  the  ground  the  molecules  of  the 
ground  support  us  by  hammering  on  the  soles  of  our 
boots  with  force  equivalent  to  some  ten  stone  weight. 
But  for  this  we  should  sink  through  the  interstices  of 
the  floor.  We  are  being  continuously  and  vigorously 
buffeted.  Now  this  can  scarcely  be  regarded  as  the  ideal 
condition  for  a  judicial  contemplation  of  our  natural 
surroundings,  and  it  would  not  be  surprising  if  our 
senses  suffering  from  this  treatment  gave  a  jaundiced 
view  of  the  world.  Our  bodies  are  to  be  regarded  as 
scientific  instruments  used  to  survey  the  world.  We 
should  not  willingly  allow  anyone  to  hammer  on  a 
galvanometer  when  it  was  being  used  for  observation; 
and  similarly  it  is  preferable  to  avoid  a  hammering  on 
one's  body  when  it  is  being  used  as  a  channel  of  scien- 
tific knowledge.  We  get  rid  of  this  hammering  when 
we  cease  to  be  supported. 

Let  us  then  take  a  leap  over  a  precipice  so  that  we 
may  contemplate  Nature  undisturbed.  Or  if  that  seems 
to  you  an  odd  way  of  convincing  yourself  that  bodies  do 
not  fall,*  let  us  enter  the  runaway  lift  again.  Here 
nothing   need   be    supported;    our   bodies,    our   galvano- 

*  So  far  as  I  can  tell  (without  experimental  trial)  the  man  who  jumped 
over  a  precipice  would  soon  lose  all  conception  of  falling;  he  would  only 
notice  that  the  surrounding  objects  were  impelled  past  him  with  ever- 
increasing   speed. 


ii4  GRAVITATION— THE  LAW 

meters,  and  all  measuring  apparatus  are  relieved  of 
hammering  and  their  indications  can  be  received  without 
misgiving.  The  space-  and  time-frame  of  the  falling  lift 
is  the  frame  natural  to  observers  who  are  unsupported; 
and  the  laws  of  Nature  determined  in  these  favourable 
circumstances  should  at  least  have  not  inferior  status  to 
those  established  by  reference  to  other  frames. 

I  perform  another  experiment.  This  time  I  take  two 
apples  and  drop  them  at  opposite  ends  of  the  lift.  What 
will  happen?  Nothing  much  at  first;  the  apples  remain 
poised  where  they  were  let  go.  But  let  us  step  outside 
the  lift  for  a  moment  to  watch  the  experiment.  The  two 
apples  are  pulled  by  gravity  towards  the  centre  of  the 
earth.  As  they  approach  the  centre  their  paths  con- 
verge and  they  will  meet  at  the  centre.  Now  step  back 
into  the  lift  again.  To  a  first  approximation  the  apples 
remain  poised  above  the  floor  of  the  lift;  but  presently 
we  notice  that  they  are  drifting  towards  one  another, 
and  they  will  meet  at  the  moment  when  (according  to 
an  outside  observer)  the  lift  is  passing  through  the 
centre  of  the  earth.  Even  though  apples  (in  the  lift) 
do  not  tend  to  fall  to  the  floor  there  is  still  a  mystery 
about  their  behaviour;  and  the  Newton  of  the  lift  may 
yet  find  that  the  agent  which  guides  the  stars  in  their 
courses  is  to  be  identified  with  the  agent  which  plays 
these  tricks  with  apples  nearer  home. 

It  comes  to  this.  There  are  both  relative  and  absolute 
features  about  gravitation.  The  feature  that  impresses 
us  most  is  relative — relative  to  a  frame  that  has  no 
special  importance  apart  from  the  fact  that  it  is  the  one 
commonly  used  by  us.  This  feature  disappears  alto- 
gether in  the  frame  of  the  man  in  the  lift  and  we  ought 
to  disregard  it  in  any  attempt  to  form  an  absolute  pic- 
ture of  gravitation.    But  there  always  remains  something 


A  NEW  PICTURE  OF  GRAVITATION  115 

absolute,  of  which  we  must  try  to  devise  an  appropriate 
picture.  For  reasons  which  I  shall  presently  explain  we 
find  that  it  can  be  pictured  as  a  curvature  of  space  and 
time. 

A  New  Picture  of  Gravitation.  The  Newtonian  picture 
of  gravitation  is  a  tug  applied  to  the  body  whose  path 
is  disturbed.  I  want  to  explain  why  this  picture  must 
be  superseded.  I  must  refer  again  to  the  famous  incident 
in  which  Newton  and  the  apple-tree  were  concerned. 
The  classical  conception  of  gravitation  is  based  on  New- 
ton's account  of  what  happened;  but  it  is  time  to  hear 
what  the  apple  had  to  say.  The  apple  with  the  usual 
egotism  of  an  observer  deemed  itself  to  be  at  rest; 
looking  down  it  saw  the  various  terrestrial  objects  includ- 
ing Newton  rushing  upwards  with  accelerated  velocity 
to  meet  it.  Does  it  invent  a  mysterious  agency  or  tug 
to  account  for  their  conduct?  No;  it  points  out  that 
the  cause  of  their  acceleration  is  quite  evident.  Newton 
is  being  hammered  by  the  molecules  of  the  ground 
underneath  him.  This  hammering  is  absolute — no  ques- 
tion of  frames  of  reference.  With  a  powerful  enough 
magnifying  appliance  anyone  can  see  the  molecules  at 
work  and  count  their  blows.  According  to  Newton's 
own  law  of  motion  this  must  give  him  an  acceleration, 
which  is  precisely  what  the  apple  has  observed.  New- 
ton had  to  postulate  a  mysterious  invisible  force  pulling 
the  apple  down;  the  apple  can  point  to  an  evident  cause 
propelling  Newton  up. 

The  case  for  the  apple's  view  is  so  overwhelming  that 
I  must  modify  the  situation  a  little  in  order  to  give 
Newton  a  fair  chance;  because  I  believe  the  apple  is 
making  too  much  of  a  merely  accidental  advantage.  I 
will   place    Newton    at   the    centre    of   the    earth   where 


u6  GRAVITATION— THE  LAW 

gravity  vanishes,  so  that  he  can  remain  at  rest  without 
support — without  hammering.  He  looks  up  and  sees 
apples  falling  at  the  surface  of  the  earth,  and  as  before 
ascribes  this  to  a  mysterious  tug  which  he  calls  gravita- 
tion. The  apple  looks  down  and  sees  Newton  approach- 
ing it;  but  this  time  it  cannot  attribute  Newton's  accelera- 
tion to  any  evident  hammering.  It  also  has  to  invent 
a  mysterious  tug  acting  on  Newton. 

We  have  two  frames  of  reference.  In  one  of  them 
Newton  is  at  rest  and  the  apple  is  accelerated;  in  the 
other  the  apple  is  at  rest  and  Newton  accelerated.  In 
neither  case  is  there  a  visible  cause  for  the  acceleration; 
in  neither  is  the  object  disturbed  by  extraneous  ham- 
mering. The  reciprocity  is  perfect  and  there  is  no  ground 
for  preferring  one  frame  rather  than  the  other.  We 
must  devise  a  picture  of  the  disturbing  agent  which  will 
not  favour  one  frame  rather  than  the  other.  In  this 
impartial  humour  a  tug  will  not  suit  us,  because  if  we 
attach  it  to  the  apple  we  are  favouring  Newton's  frame 
and  if  we  attach  it  to  Newton  we  are  favouring  the 
apple's  frame.*  The  essence  or  absolute  part  of  gravi- 
tation cannot  be  a  force  on  a  body,  because  we  are  en- 
tirely vague  as  to  the  body  to  which  it  is  applied.  We 
must  picture  it  differently. 

*  It  will  probably  be  objected  that  since  the  phenomena  here  dis- 
cussed are  evidently  associated  with  the  existence  of  a  massive  body  (the 
earth),  and  since  Newton  makes  his  tugs  occur  symmetrically  about  that 
body  whereas  the  apple  makes  its  tugs  occur  unsymmetrically  (vanishing 
where  the  apple  is,  but  strong  at  the  antipodes),  therefore  Newton's 
frame  is  clearly  to  be  preferred.  It  would  be  necessary  to  go  deeply  into 
the  theory  to  explain  fully  why  we  do  not  regard  this  symmetry  as  of 
first  importance ;  we  can  only  say  here  that  the  criterion  of  symmetry 
proves  to  be  insufficient  to  pick  out  a  unique  frame  and  does  not  draw 
a  sharp  dividing  line  between  the  frames  that  it  would  admit  and  those 
it  would  have  us  reject.  After  all  we  can  appreciate  that  certain  frames 
are  more  symmetrical  than  others  without  insisting  on  calling  the  sym- 
metrical ones  '"right"'  and  unsymmetrical  ones  'wrong'. 


A  NEW  PICTURE  OF  GRAVITATION  117 

The  ancients  believed  that  the  earth  was  flat.  The 
small  part  which  they  had  explored  could  be  represented 
without  serious  distortion  on  a  flat  map.  When  new 
countries  were  discovered  it  would  be  natural  to  think 
that  they  could  be  added  on  to  the  flat  map.  A  familiar 
example  of  such  a  flat  map  is  Mercator's  projection,  and 
you  will  remember  that  in  it  the  size  of  Greenland 
appears  absurdly  exaggerated.  (In  other  projections 
directions  are  badly  distorted.)  Now  those  who  adhered 
to  the  flat-earth  theory  must  suppose  that  the  map  gives 
the  true  size  of  Greenland — that  the  distances  shown  in 
the  map  are  the  true  distances.  How  then  wrould  they 
explain  that  travellers  in  that  country  reported  that  the 
distances  seemed  to  be  much  shorter  than  they  "really" 
were  ?  They  would,  I  suppose,  invent  a  theory  that  there 
was  a  demon  living  in  Greenland  who  helped  travellers 
on  their  way.  Of  course  no  scientist  would  use  so  crude 
a  word;  he  would  invent  a  Graeco-Latin  polysyllable  to 
denote  the  mysterious  agent  which  made  the  journeys 
seem  so  short;  but  that  is  only  camouflage.  But  now 
suppose  the  inhabitants  of  Greenland  have  developed 
their  own  geography.  They  find  that  the  most  important 
part  of  the  earth's  surface  (Greenland)  can  be  repre- 
sented without  serious  distortion  on  a  flat  map.  But 
when  they  put  in  distant  countries  such  as  Greece  the 
size  must  be  exaggerated;  or,  as  they  would  put  it,  there 
is  a  demon  active  in  Greece  who  makes  the  journeys 
there  seem  different  from  what  the  flat  map  clearly 
shows  them  to  be.  The  demon  is  never  where  you  are; 
it  is  always  the  other  fellow  who  is  haunted  by  him. 
We  now  understand  that  the  true  explanation  is  that  the 
earth  is  curved,  and  the  apparent  activities  of  the  demon 
arise  from  forcing  the  curved  surface  into  a  flat  map 
and  so  distorting  the  simplicity  of  things. 


u8  GRAVITATION— THE  LAW 

What  has  happened  to  the  theory  of  the  earth  has 
happened  also  to  the  theory  of  the  world  of  space-time. 
An  observer  at  rest  at  the  earth's  centre  represents  what 
is  happening  in  a  frame  of  space  and  time  constructed 
on  the  usual  conventional  principles  which  give  what 
is  called  a  flat  space-time.  He  can  locate  the  events  in 
his  neighbourhood  without  distorting  their  natural  sim- 
plicity. Objects  at  rest  remain  at  rest;  objects  in  uni- 
form motion  remain  in  uniform  motion  unless  there  is 
some  evident  cause  of  disturbance  such  as  hammering; 
light  travels  in  straight  lines.  He  extends  this  flat  frame 
to  the  surface  of  the  earth  where  he  encounters  the 
phenomenon  of  falling  apples.  This  new  phenomenon  has 
to  be  accounted  for  by  an  intangible  agency  or  demon 
called  gravitation  which  persuades  the  apples  to  deviate 
from  their  proper  uniform  motion.  But  we  can  also  start 
with  the  frame  of  the  falling  apple  or  of  the  man  in  the 
lift.  In  the  lift-frame  bodies  at  rest  remain  at  rest;  bodies 
in  uniform  motion  remain  in  uniform  motion.  But,  as  we 
have  seen,  even  at  the  corners  of  the  lift  this  simplicity 
begins  to  fail;  and  looking  further  afield,  say  to  the 
centre  of  the  earth,  it  is  necessary  to  postulate  the  acti- 
vity of  a  demon  urging  unsupported  bodies  upwards 
(relatively  to  the  lift-frame).  As  we  change  from  one 
observer  to  another — from  one  flat  space-time  frame  to 
another — the  scene  of  activity  of  the  demon  shifts.  It 
is  never  where  our  observer  is,  but  always  away  yonder. 
Is  not  the  solution  now  apparent?  The  demon  is  sim- 
ply the  complication  which  arises  when  we  try  to  fit  a 
curved  world  into  a  flat  frame.  In  referring  the  world 
to  a  flat  frame  of  space-time  we  distort  it  so  that  the 
phenomena  do  not  appear  in  their  original  simplicity. 
Admit  a  curvature  of  the  world  and  the  mysterious 
agency  disappears.     Einstein  has  exorcised  the  demon. 


A  NEW  LAW  OF  GRAVITATION  119 

Do  not  imagine  that  this  preliminary  change  of  con- 
ception carries  us  very  far  towards  an  explanation  of 
gravitation.  We  are  not  seeking  an  explanation;  we 
are  seeking  a  picture.  And  this  picture  of  world- 
curvature  (hard  though  it  may  seem)  is  more  graspable 
than  an  elusive  tug  which  flits  from  one  object  to 
another  according  to  the  point  of  view  chosen. 

A  New  Law  of  Gravitation.  Having  found  a  new  pic- 
ture of  gravitation,  we  require  a  new  law  of  gravitation; 
for  the  Newtonian  law  told  us  the  arcounr.  of  the  tug 
and  there  is  now  no  tug  to  be  considered.  Since  the 
phenomenon  is  now  pictured  as  curvature  the  new  law 
must  say  something  about  curvature.  Evidently  it  must 
be  a  law  governing  and  limiting  the  possible  curvature 
of  space-time. 

There  are  not  many  things  which  can  be  said  about 
curvature — not  many  of  a  general  character.  So  that 
when  Einstein  felt  this  urgency  to  say  something  about 
curvature,  he  almost  automatically  said  the  right  thing. 
I  mean  that  there  was  only  one  limitation  or  law  that 
suggested  itself  as  reasonable,  and  that  law  has  proved 
to  be  right  when  tested  by  observation. 

Some  of  you  may  feel  that  you  could  never  bring  your 
minds  to  conceive  a  curvature  of  space,  let  alone  of 
space-time;  others  may  feel  that,  being  familiar  with 
the  bending  of  a  two-dimensional  surface,  there  is  no 
insuperable  difficulty  in  imagining  something  similar  for 
three  or  even  four  dimensions.  I  rather  think  that 
the  former  have  the  best  of  it,  for  at  least  they  escape 
being  misled  by  their  preconceptions.  I  have  spoken  of 
a  "picture",  but  it  is  a  picture  that  has  to  be  described 
analytically  rather  than  conceived  vividly.  Our  ordinary 
conception   of   curvature   is   derived   from   surfaces,    i.e. 


120  GRAVITATION— THE  LAW 

two-dimensional  manifolds  embedded  in  a  three-dimen- 
sional space.  The  absolute  curvature  at  any  point  is 
measured  by  a  single  quantity  called  the  radius  of  spheri- 
cal curvature.  But  space-time  is  a  four-dimensional 
manifold  embedded  in — well,  as  many  dimensions  as  it 
can  find  new  ways  to  twist  about  in.  Actually  a  four- 
dimensional  manifold  is  amazingly  ingenious  in  discover- 
ing new  kinds  of  contortion,  and  its  invention  is  not 
exhausted  until  it  has  been  provided  with  six  extra 
dimensions,  making  ten  dimensions  in  all.  Moreover, 
twenty  distinct  measures  are  required  at  each  point  to 
specify  the  particular  sort  and  amount  of  twistiness 
there.  These  measures  are  called  coefficients  of  curva- 
ture. Ten  of  the  coefficients  stand  out  more  prominently 
than  the  other  ten. 

Einstein's  law  of  gravitation  asserts  that  the  ten  prin- 
cipal coefficients  of  curvature  are  zero  in  empty  space. 

If  there  were  no  curvature,  i.e.  if  all  the  coefficients 
were  zero,  there  would  be  no  gravitation.  Bodies  would 
move  uniformly  in  straight  lines.  If  curvature  were 
unrestricted,  i.e.  if  all  the  coefficients  had  unpredictable 
values,  gravitation  would  operate  arbitrarily  and  with- 
out law.  Bodies  would  move  just  anyhow.  Einstein 
takes  a  condition  midway  between;  ten  of  the  coefficients 
are  zero  and  the  other  ten  are  arbitrary.  That  gives 
a  world  containing  gravitation  limited  by  a  law.  The 
coefficients  are  naturally  separated  into  two  groups  of 
ten,  so  that  there  is  no  difficulty  in  choosing  those  which 
are  to  vanish. 

To  the  uninitiated  it  may  seem  surprising  that  an 
exact  law  of  Nature  should  leave  some  of  the  coefficients 
arbitrary.  But  we  need  to  leave  something  over  to  be 
settled  when  we  have  specified  the  particulars  of  the 
problem  to  which  it  is  proposed  to  apply  the  law.     A 


A  NEW  LAW  OF  GRAVITATION  121 

general  law  covers  an  infinite  number  of  special  cases. 
The  vanishing  of  the  ten  principal  coefficients  occurs 
everywhere  in  empty  space  whether  there  is  one  gravi- 
tating body  or  many.  The  other  ten  coefficients  vary 
according  to  the  special  case  under  discussion.  This  may 
remind  us  that  after  reaching  Einstein's  law  of  gravi- 
tation and  formulating  it  mathematically,  it  is  still  a  very 
long  step  to  reach  its  application  to  even  the  simplest 
practical  problem.  However,  by  this  time  many  hun- 
dreds of  readers  must  have  gone  carefully  through  the 
mathematics;  so  we  may  rest  assured  that  there  has 
been  no  mistake.  After  this  work  has  been  done  it 
becomes  possible  to  verify  that  the  law  agrees  with 
observation.  It  is  found  that  it  agrees  with  Newton's 
law  to  a  very  close  approximation  so  that  the  main 
evidence  for  Einstein's  law  is  the  same  as  the  evidence 
for  Newton's  law;  but  there  are  three  crucial  astro- 
nomical phenomena  in  which  the  difference  is  large 
enough  to  be  observed.  In  these  phenomena  the  obser- 
vations support  Einstein's  law  against  Newton's.* 

It  is  essential  to  our  faith  in  a  theory  that  its  predic- 
tions should  accord  with  observation,  unless  a  reasonable 
explanation  of  the  discrepancy  is  forthcoming;  so  that 
it  is  highly  important  that  Einstein's  law  should  have 
survived  these  delicate  astronomical  tests  in  which  New- 
ton's law  just  failed.  But  our  main  reason  for  reject- 
ing Newton's  law  is  not  its  imperfect  accuracy  as  shown 
by  these  tests;  it  is  because  it  does  not  contain  the 
kind  of  information  about  Nature  that  we  want  to 
know  now  that  we  have  an  ideal  before  us  which  was 
not  in  Newton's  mind  at  all.     We  can  put  it  this  way. 

*  One  of  the  tests — a  shift  of  the  spectral  lines  to  the  red  in  the  sun 
and  stars  as  compared  with  terrestrial  sources — is  a  test  of  Einstein's 
theory  rather  than  of  his  law. 


122  GRAVITATION— THE  LAW 

Astronomical  observations  show  that  within  certain 
limits  of  accuracy  both  Einstein's  and  Newton's  laws 
are  true.  In  confirming  (approximately)  Newton's  law, 
we  are  confirming  a  statement  as  to  what  the  appear- 
ances would  be  when  referred  to  one  particular  space- 
time  frame.  No  reason  is  given  for  attaching  any 
fundamental  importance  to  this  frame.  In  confirming 
(approximately)  Einstein's  law,  we  are  confirming  a 
statement  about  the  absolute  properties  of  the  world, 
true  for  all  space-time  frames.  For  those  who  are  try- 
ing to  get  beneath  the  appearances  Einstein's  statement 
necessarily  supersedes  Newton's;  it  extracts  from  the 
observations  a  result  with  physical  meaning  as  opposed 
to  a  mathematical  curiosity.  That  Einstein's  law  has 
proved  itself  the  better  approximation  encourages  us  in 
our  opinion  that  the  quest  of  the  absolute  is  the  best  way 
to  understand  the  relative  appearances;  but  had  the  suc- 
cess been  less  immediate,  we  could  scarcely  have  turned 
our  back  on  the  quest. 

I  cannot  but  think  that  Newton  himself  would  rejoice 
that  after  200  years  the  "ocean  of  undiscovered  truth" 
has  rolled  back  another  stage.  I  do  not  think  of  him  as 
censorious  because  we  will  not  blindly  apply  his  formula 
regardless  of  the  knowledge  that  has  since  accumulated 
and  in  circumstances  that  he  never  had  the  opportunity 
of  considering. 

I  am  not  going  to  describe  the  three  tests  here,  since 
they  are  now  well  known  and  will  be  found  in  any  of 
the  numerous  guides  to  relativity;  but  I  would  refer  to 
the  action  of  gravitation  on  light  concerned  in  one  of 
them.  Light-waves  in  passing  a  massive  body  such  as 
the  sun  are  deflected  through  a  small  angle.  This  is 
additional  evidence  that  the  Newtonian  picture  of 
gravitation  as  a  tug  is  inadequate.     You  cannot  deflect 


THE  LAW  OF  MOTION  123 

waves  by  tugging  at  them,  and  clearly  another  repre- 
sentation of  the  agency  which  deflects  them  must  be 
found. 

The  Law  of  Motion.  I  must  now  ask  you  to  let  your 
mind  revert  to  the  time  of  your  first  introduction  to 
mechanics  before  your  natural  glimmerings  of  the  truth 
were  sedulously  uprooted  by  your  teacher.  You  were 
taught  the  First  Law  of  Motion — 

"Every  body  continues  in  its  state  of  rest  or  uniform 
motion  in  a  straight  line,  except  in  so  far  as  it  may  be 
compelled  to  change  that  state  by  impressed  forces." 

Probably  you  had  previously  supposed  that  motion 
was  something  which  would  exhaust  itself;  a  bicycle 
stops  of  its  own  accord  if  you  do  not  impress  force  to 
keep  it  going.  The  teacher  rightly  pointed  out  the 
resisting  forces  which  tend  to  stop  the  bicycle;  and  he 
probably  quoted  the  example  of  a  stone  skimming  over 
ice  to  show  that  when  these  interfering  forces  are  re- 
duced the  motion  lasts  much  longer.  But  even  ice  offers 
some  frictional  resistance.  Why  did  not  the  teacher  do 
the  thing  thoroughly  and  abolish  resisting  forces  alto- 
gether, as  he  might  easily  have  done  by  projecting  the 
stone  into  empty  space?  Unfortunately  in  that  case 
its  motion  is  not  uniform  and  rectilinear;  the  stone 
describes  a  parabola.  If  you  raised  that  objection  you 
would  be  told  that  the  projectile  was  compelled  to 
change  its  state  of  uniform  motion  by  an  invisible  force 
called  gravitation.  How  do  we  know  that  this  invisible 
force  exists?  Why!  because  if  the  force  did  not  exist 
the  projectile  would  move  uniformly  in  a  straight  line. 

The  teacher  is  not  playing  fair.  He  is  determined  to 
have  his  uniform  motion  in  a  straight  line,  and  if  we 
point  out  to  him  bodies  which  do  not  follow  his  rule 


124  GRAVITATION— THE  LAW 

he  blandly  invents  a  new  force  to  account  for  the  devia- 
tion. We  can  improve  on  his  enunciation  of  the  First 
Law  of  Motion.     What  he  really  meant  was — 

"Every  body  continues  in  its  state  of  rest  or  uniform 
motion  in  a  straight  line,  except  in  so  far  as  it  doesn't." 

Material  frictions  and  reactions  are  visible  and  abso- 
lute interferences  which  can  change  the  motion  of  a 
body.  I  have  nothing  to  say  against  them.  The  mole- 
cular battering  can  be  recognised  by  anyone  who  looks 
deeply  into  the  phenomenon  no  matter  what  his  frame 
of  reference.  But  when  there  is  no  such  indication  of 
disturbance  the  whole  procedure  becomes  arbitrary.  On 
no  particular  grounds  the  motion  is  divided  into  two 
parts,  one  of  which  is  attributed  to  a  passive  tendency 
of  the  body  called  inertia  and  the  other  to  an  interfer- 
ing field  of  force.  The  suggestion  that  the  body  really 
wanted  to  go  straight  but  some  mysterious  agent  made 
it  go  crooked  is  picturesque  but  unscientific.  It  makes 
two  properties  out  of  one;  and  then  we  wonder  why  they 
are  always  proportional  to  one  another — why  the  gravi- 
tational force  on  different  bodies  is  proportional  to 
their  inertia  or  mass.  The  dissection  becomes  untenable 
when  we  admit  that  all  frames  of  reference  are  on  the 
same  footing.  The  projectile  which  describes  a  parabola 
relative  to  an  observer  on  the  earth's  surface  describes 
a  straight  line  relative  to  the  man  in  the  lift.  Our 
teacher  will  not  easily  persuade  the  man  in  the  lift  who 
sees  the  apple  remaining  where  he  released  it,  that  the 
apple  really  would  of  its  own  initiative  rush  upwards 
were  it  not  that  an  invisible  tug  exactly  counteracts  this 
tendency.* 

Einstein's  Law  of  Motion  does  not  recognise  this 
dissection.     There    are    certain    curves    which    can    be 

*  The  reader  will  verify  tkat  this  is  the  doctrine  the  teacher  would  have 
to  inculcate  if  he  went  as  a  missionary  to  the  men  in  the  lift. 


THE  LAW  OF  MOTION  125 

defined  on  a  curved  surface  without  reference  to  any 
frame  or  system  of  partitions,  viz.  the  geodesies  or 
shortest  routes  from  one  point  to  another.  The  geo- 
desies of  our  curved  space-time  supply  the  natural  tracks 
which  particles   pursue  if  they  are   undisturbed. 

We  observe  a  planet  wandering  round  the  sun  in  an 
elliptic  orbit.  A  little  consideration  will  show  that  if  we 
add  a  fourth  dimension  (time),  the  continual  moving  on 
in  the  time-dimension  draws  out  the  ellipse  into  a  helix. 
Why  does  the  planet  take  this  spiral  track  instead  of 
going  straight?  It  is  because  it  is  following  the  shortest 
track;  and  in  the  distorted  geometry  of  the  curved 
region  round  the  sun  the  spiral  track  is  shorter  than  any 
other  between  the  same  points.  You  see  the  great 
change  in  our  view.  The  Newtonian  scheme  says  that 
the  planet  tends  to  move  in  a  straight  line,  but  the  sun's 
gravity  pulls  it  away.  Einstein  says  that  the  planet  tends 
to  take  the  shortest  route  and  does  take  it. 

That  is  the  general  idea,  but  for  the  sake  of  accuracy 
I  must  make  one  rather  trivial  correction.  The  planet 
takes  the  longest  route. 

You  may  remember  that  points  along  the  track  of 
any  material  body  (necessarily  moving  with  a  speed  less 
than  the  velocity  of  light)  are  in  the  absolute  past  or 
future  of  one  another;  they  are  not  absolutely  ''else- 
where". Hence  the  length  of  the  track  in  four  dimensions 
is  made  up  of  time-like  relations  and  must  be  measured 
in  time-units.  It  is  in  fact  the  number  of  seconds 
recorded  by  a  clock  carried  on  a  body  which  describes 
the  track.*     This  may  be  different  from  the  time   re- 

*  It  may  be  objected  that  you  cannot  make  a  clock  follow  an  arbitrary 
curved  path  without  disturbing  it  by  impressed  forces  (e.g.  molecular 
hammering).  But  this  difficulty  is  precisely  analogous  to  the  difficulty 
of  measuring  the  length  of  a  curve  with  a  rectilinear  scale,  and  is  sur- 
mounted in  the  same  way.  The  usual  theory  of  "rectification  of  curves" 
applies  to  these  time-tracks  as  well  as  to  space-curves. 


126  GRAVITATION— THE  LAW 

corded  by  a  clock  which  has  taken  some  other  route 
between  the  same  terminal  points.  On  p.  39  we  con- 
sidered two  individuals  whose  tracks  had  the  same 
terminal  points;  one  of  them  remained  at  home  on  the 
earth  and  the  other  travelled  at  high  speed  to  a  distant 
part  of  the  universe  and  back.  The  first  recorded  a 
lapse  of  70  years,  the  second  of  one  year.  Notice  that 
it  is  the  man  who  follows  the  undisturbed  track  of  the 
earth  who  records  or  lives  the  longest  time.  The  man 
whose  track  was  violently  dislocated  when  he  reached 
the  limit  of  his  journey  and  started  to  come  back  again 
lived  only  one  year.  There  is  no  limit  to  this  reduction; 
as  the  speed  of  the  traveller  approaches  the  speed  of 
light  the  time  recorded  diminishes  to  zero.  There  is  no 
unique  shortest  track;  but  the  longest  track  is  unique. 
If  instead  of  pursuing  its  actual  orbit  the  earth  made  a 
wide  sweep  which  required  it  to  travel  with  the  velocity 
of  light,  the  earth  could  get  from  1  January  1927  to  1 
January  1928  in  no  time,  i.e.  no  time  as  recorded  by  an 
observer  or  clock  travelling  with  it,  though  it  would  be 
reckoned  as  a  year  according  to  "Astronomer  Royal's 
time".  The  earth  does  not  do  this,  because  it  is  a  rule 
of  the  Trade  Union  of  matter  that  the  longest  possible 
time  must  be  taken  over  every  job. 

Thus  in  calculating  astronomical  orbits  and  in  similar 
problems  two  laws  are  involved.  We  must  first  cal- 
culate the  curved  form  of  space-time  by  using  Einstein's 
law  of  gravitation,  viz.  that  the  ten  principal  curva- 
tures are  zero.  We  next  calculate  how  the  planet  moves 
through  the  curved  region  by  using  Einstein's  law  of 
motion,  viz.  the  law  of  the  longest  track.  Thus  far  the 
procedure  is  analogous  to  calculations  made  with  New- 
ton's law  of  gravitation  and  Newton's  law  of  motion. 
But  there  is  a  remarkable  addendum  which  applies  only 


THE  LAW  OF  MOTION  127 

to  Einstein's  laws.  Einstein's  law  of  motion  can  be 
deduced  from  his  law  of  gravitation.  The  prediction  of 
the  track  of  a  planet  although  divided  into  two  stages 
for  convenience  rests  on  a  single  law. 

I  should  like  to  show  you  in  a  general  way  how  it  is 
possible  for  a  law  controlling  the  curvature  of  empty 
space  to  determine  the  tracks  of  particles  without  being 
supplemented  by  any  other  conditions.  Two  "particles"  in 
the  four-dimensional  world  are  shown  in  Fig.  5,  namely 
yourself  and  myself.  We  are  not  empty  space  so  there  is 


—  ^-"^ 


Fig.  5 

no  limit  to  the  kind  of  curvature  entering  into  our  com- 
position; in  fact  our  unusual  sort  of  curvature  is  what 
distinguishes  us  from  empty  space.  We  are,  so  to 
speak,  ridges  in  the  four-dimensional  world  where  it  is 
gathered  into  a  pucker.  The  pure  mathematician  in  his 
unflattering  language  would  describe  us  as  "singulari- 
ties". These  two  non-empty  ridges  are  joined  by  empty 
space,  which  must  be  free  from  those  kinds  of  curva- 
ture described  by  the  ten  principal  coefficients.  Now 
it  is  common  experience  that  if  we  introduce  local 
puckers  into  the  material  of  a  garment,  the  remainder 
has  a  certain  obstinacy  and  will  not  lie  as  smoothly  as 


128  GRAVITATION— THE  LAW 

we  might  wish.  You  will  realise  the  possibility  that, 
given  two  ridges  as  in  Fig.  5,  it  may  be  impossible  to 
join  them  by  an  intervening  valley  without  the  illegal 
kind  of  curvature.  That  turns  out  to  be  the  case.  Two 
perfectly  straight  ridges  alone  in  the  world  cannot  be 
properly  joined  by  empty  space  and  therefore  they  can- 
not occur  alone.  But  if  they  bend  a  little  towards  one 
another  the  connecting  region  can  lie  smoothly  and  sat- 
isfy the  law  of  curvature.  If  they  bend  too  much  the 
illegal  puckering  reappears.  The  law  of  gravitation  is 
a  fastidious  tailor  who  will  not  tolerate  wrinkles  (except 
of  a  limited  approved  type)  in  the  main  area  of  the 
garment;  so  that  the  seams  are  required  to  take  courses 
which  will  not  cause  wrinkles.  You  and  I  have  to  sub- 
mit to  this  and  so  our  tracks  curve  towards  each  other. 
An  onlooker  will  make  the  comment  that  here  is  an 
illustration  of  the  law  that  two  massive  bodies  attract 
each  other. 

We  thus  arrive  at  another  but  equivalent  conception 
of  how  the  earth's  spiral  track  through  the  four-dimen- 
sional world  is  arrived  at.  It  is  due  to  the  necessity  of 
arranging  two  ridges  (the  solar  track  and  the  earth's 
track)  so  as  not  to  involve  a  wrong  kind  of  curvature  in 
the  empty  part  of  the  world.  The  sun  as  the  more 
pronounced  ridge  takes  a  nearly  straight  track;  but  the 
earth  as  a  minor  ridge  on  the  declivities  of  the  solar 
ridge  has   to  twist  about  considerably. 

Suppose  the  earth  were  to  defy  the  tailor  and  take  a 
straight  track.  That  would  make  a  horrid  wrinkle  in  the 
garment;  and  since  the  wrinkle  is  inconsistent  with  the 
laws  of  empty  space,  something  must  be  there — where 
the  wrinkle  runs.  This  "something"  need  not  be  matter 
in  the  restricted  sense.  The  things  which  can  occupy 
space   so  that  it  is  not  empty  in  the  sense  intended  in 


RELATIVITY  OF  ACCELERATION  129 

Einstein's  law,  are  mass  (or  its  equivalent  energy) 
momentum  and  stress  (pressure  or  tension).  In  this  case 
the  wrinkle  might  correspond  to  stress.  That  is  reason- 
able enough.  If  left  alone  the  earth  must  pursue  its 
proper  curved  orbit;  but  if  some  kind  of  stress  or  pres- 
sure were  inserted  between  the  sun  and  earth,  it  might 
well  take  another  course.  In  fact  if  we  were  to  observe 
one  of  the  planets  rushing  off  in  a  straight  track,  New- 
tonians and  Einsteinians  alike  would  infer  that  there 
existed  a  stress  causing  this  behaviour.  It  is  true  that 
causation  has  apparently  been  turned  topsy-turvy;  ac- 
cording to  our  theory  the  stress  seems  to  be  caused  by 
the  planet  taking  the  wrong  track,  whereas  we  usually 
suppose  that  the  planet  takes  the  wrong  track  because  it 
is  acted  on  by  the  stress.  But  that  is  a  harmless  accident 
common  enough  in  primary  physics.  The  discrimination 
between  cause  and  effect  depends  on  time's  arrow  and 
can  only  be  settled  by  reference  to  entropy.  We  need 
not  pay  much  attention  to  suggestions  of  causation  aris- 
ing in  discussions  of  primary  laws  which,  as  likely  as 
not,  are  contemplating  the  world  upside  down. 

Although  we  are  here  only  at  the  beginning  of  Ein- 
stein's general  theory  I  must  not  proceed  further  into 
this  very  technical  subject.  The  rest  of  this  chapter  will 
be  devoted  to  elucidation  of  more  elementary  points. 

Relativity  of  Acceleration.  The  argument  in  this  chapter 
rests  on  the  relativity  of  acceleration.  The  apple  had  an 
acceleration  of  32  feet  per  second  per  second  relative  to 
the  ordinary  observer,  but  zero  acceleration  relative  to 
the  man  in  the  lift.  We  ascribe  to  it  one  acceleration  or 
the  other  according  to  the  frame  we  happen  to  be  using, 
but  neither  is  to  be  singled  out  and  labelled  "true" 
or    absolute    acceleration.      That   led    us   to    reject    the 


i3o  GRAVITATION— THE  LAW 

Newtonian  conception  which  singled  out  32  feet  per 
second  per  second  as  the  true  acceleration  and  invented 
a  disturbing  agent  of  this  particular  degree  of  strength. 

It  will  be  instructive  to  consider  an  objection  brought, 
I  think,  originally  by  Lenard.  A  train  is  passing  through 
a  station  at  60  miles  an  hour.  Since  velocity  is  relative, 
it  does  not  matter  whether  we  say  that  the  train  is 
moving  at  60  miles  an  hour  past  the  station  or  the 
station  is  moving  at  60  miles  an  hour  past  the  train. 
Now  suppose,  as  sometimes  happens  in  railway  acci- 
dents, that  this  motion  is  brought  to  a  standstill  in  a 
few  seconds.  There  has  been  a  change  of  velocity  or 
acceleration — a  term  which  includes  deceleration.  If 
acceleration  is  relative  this  may  be  described  indiffer- 
ently as  an  acceleration  of  the  train  (relative  to  the  sta- 
tion) or  an  acceleration  of  the  station  (relative  to  the 
train).  Why  then  does  it  injure  the  persons  in  the  train 
and  not  those  in  the  station? 

Much  the  same  point  was  put  to  me  by  one  of  my 
audience.  "You  must  find  the  journey  between  Cam- 
bridge and  Edinburgh  very  tiring.  I  can  understand 
the  fatigue,  if  you  travel  to  Edinburgh;  but  why  should 
you  get  tired  if  Edinburgh  comes  to  you?"  The  answer 
is  that  the  fatigue  arises  from  being  shut  up  in  a  box 
and  jolted  about  for  nine  hours;  and  it  makes  no  differ- 
ence whether  in  the  meantime  I  move  to  Edinburgh  or 
Edinburgh  moves  to  me.  Motion  does  not  tire  anybody. 
With  the  earth  as  our  vehicle  we  are  travelling  at  20 
miles  a  second  round  the  sun;  the  sun  carries  us  at  12 
miles  a  second  through  the  galactic  system;  the  galactic 
system  bears  us  at  250  miles  a  second  amid  the  spiral 
nebulae;  the  spiral  nebulae.  ...  If  motion  could  tire, 
we  ought  to  be  dead  tired. 

Similarly  change  of  motion  or  acceleration  does  not 


RELATIVITY  OF  ACCELERATION  131 

injure  anyone,  even  when  it  is  (according  to  the  New- 
tonian view)  an  absolute  acceleration.  We  do  not  even 
feel  the  change  of  motion  as  our  earth  takes  the  curve 
round  the  sun.  We  feel  something  when  a  railway  train 
takes  a  curve,  but  what  we  feel  is  not  the  change  of 
motion  nor  anything  which  invariably  accompanies 
change  of  motion;  it  is  something  incidental  to  the 
curved  track  of  the  train  but  not  to  the  curved  track  of 
the  earth.  The  cause  of  injury  in  the  railway  accident 
is  easily  traced.  Something  hit  the  train;  that  is  to  say, 
the  train  was  bombarded  by  a  swarm  of  molecules  and 
the  bombardment  spread  all  the  way  along  it.  The 
cause  is  evident — gross,  material,  absolute — recognised 
by  everyone,  no  matter  what  his  frame  of  reference, 
as  occurring  in  the  train  not  the  station.  Besides  injur- 
ing the  passengers  this  cause  also  produced  the  relative 
acceleration  of  the  train  and  station — an  effect  which 
might  equally  well  have  been  produced  by  molecular 
bombardment  of  the  station,  though  in  this  case  it  was 

not 

The  critical  reader  will  probably  pursue  his  objection. 
"Are  you  not  being  paradoxical  when  you  say  that  a 
molecular  bombardment  of  the  train  can  cause  an  accel- 
eration of  the  station — and  in  fact  of  the  earth  and  the 
rest  of  the  universe?  To  put  it  mildly,  relative  accelera- 
tion is  a  relation  with  two  ends  to  it,  and  we  may  at 
first  seem  to  have  an  option  which  end  we  shall  grasp 
it  by;  but  in  this  case  the  causation  (molecular  bom- 
bardment) clearly  indicates  the  right  end  to  take  hold 
of,  and  you  are  merely  spinning  paradoxes  when  you 
insist  on  your  liberty  to  take  hold  of  the  other." 

If  there  is  an  absurdity  in  taking  hold  of  the  wrong 
end  of  the  relation  it  has  passed  into  our  current 
speech  and  thought.     Your  suggestion  is  in  fact  more 


132  GRAVITATION— THE  LAW 

revolutionary  than  anything  Einstein  has  ventured  to 
advocate.  Let  us  take  the  problem  of  a  falling  stone. 
There  is  a  relative  acceleration  of  32  feet  per  second 
per  second — of  the  stone  relative  to  ourselves  or  of  our- 
selves relative  to  the  stone.  Which  end  of  the  relation 
must  we  choose?  The  one  indicated  by  molecular  bom- 
bardment? Well,  the  stone  is  not  bombarded;  it  is 
falling  freely  in  vacuo.  But  we  are  bombarded  by  the 
molecules  of  the  ground  on  which  we  stand.  Therefore 
it  is  we  who  have  the  acceleration;  the  stone  has  zero 
acceleration,  as  the  man  in  the  lift  supposed.  Your  sug- 
gestion makes  out  the  frame  of  the  man  in  the  lift  to 
be  the  only  legitimate  one;  I  only  went  so  far  as  to 
admit  it  to  an  equality  with  our  own  customary  frame. 

Your  suggestion  would  accept  the  testimony  of  the 
drunken  man  who  explained  that  uthe  paving-stone  got 
up  and  hit  him"  and  dismiss  the  policeman's  account  of 
the  incident  as  "merely  spinning  paradoxes".  What 
really  happened  was  that  the  paving-stone  had  been 
pursuing  the  man  through  space  with  ever-increasing 
velocity,  shoving  the  man  in  front  of  it  so  that  they  kept 
the  same  relative  position.  Then,  through  an  unfor- 
tunate wobble  of  the  axis  of  the  man's  body,  he  failed 
to  increase  his  speed  sufficiently,  with  the  result  that 
the  paving-stone  overtook  him  and  came  in  contact  with 
his  head.  That,  please  understand,  is  your  suggestion; 
or  rather  the  suggestion  which  I  have  taken  the  liberty 
of  fathering  on  you  because  it  is  the  outcome  of  a  very 
common  feeling  of  objection  to  the  relativity  theory. 
Einstein's  position  is  that  whilst  this  is  a  perfectly 
legitimate  way  of  looking  at  the  incident  the  more  usual 
account  given  by  the  policeman  is  also  legitimate;  and 
he  endeavours  like  a  good  magistrate  to  reconcile  them 
both. 


TIME  GEOMETRY  133 

Time  Geometry.  Einstein's  law  of  gravitation  controls 
a  geometrical  quantity  curvature  in  contrast  to  Newton's 
law  which  controls  a  mechanical  quantity  force.  To 
understand  the  origin  of  this  geometrisation  of  the  world 
in  the  relativity  theory  we  must  go  back  a  little. 

The  science  which  deals  with  the  properties  of  space 
is  called  geometry.  Hitherto  geometry  has  not  included 
time  in  its  scope.  But  now  space  and  time  are  so  inter- 
locked that  there  must  be  one  science — a  somewhat 
extended  geometry — embracing  them  both.  Three- 
dimensional  space  is  only  a  section  cut  through  four- 
dimensional  space-time,  and  moreover  sections  cut  in 
different  directions  form  the  spaces  of  different 
observers.  We  can  scarcely  maintain  that  the  study  of 
a  section  cut  in  one  special  direction  is  the  proper  sub- 
ject-matter of  geometry  and  that  the  study  of  slightly 
different  sections  belongs  to  an  altogether  different 
science.  Hence  the  geometry  of  the  world  is  now  con- 
sidered to  include  time  as  well  as  space.  Let  us  follow 
up  the  geometry  of  time. 

You  will  remember  that  although  space  and  time  are 
mixed  up  there  is  an  absolute  distinction  between  a 
spatial  and  a  temporal  relation  of  two  events.  Three 
events  will  form  a  space-triangle  if  the  three  sides 
correspond  to  spatial  relations — if  the  three  events  are 
absolutely  elsewhere  with  respect  to  one  another.* 
Three  events  will  form  a  time-triangle  if  the  three  sides 
correspond  to  temporal  relations — if  the  three  events 
are  absolutely  before  or  after  one  another.  (It  is  pos- 
sible also  to  have  mixed  triangles  with  two  sides  time-like 
and  one  space-like,  or  vice  versa.)  A  well-known  law 
of  the  space-triangle  is  that  any  two  sides  are  together 

*  This  would  be  an  instantaneous  space-triangle.    An  enduring  triangle 
is  a  kind  of  four-dimensional  prism. 


134  GRAVITATION— THE  LAW 

greater  than  the  third  side.  There  is  an  analogous,  but 
significantly  different,  law  for  the  time-triangle,  viz.  two 
of  the  sides  (not  any  two  sides)  are  together  less  than 
the  third  side.  It  is  difficult  to  picture  such  a  triangle 
but  that  is  the  actual  fact. 

Let  us  be  quite  sure  that  we  grasp  the  precise  mean- 
ing of  these  geometrical  propositions.  Take  first  the 
space-triangle.  The  proposition  refers  to  the  lengths  of 
the  sides,  and  it  is  well  to  recall  my  imaginary  discus- 
sion with  two  students  as  to  how  lengths  are  to  be 
measured  (p.  23).  Happily  there  is  no  ambiguity 
now,  because  the  triangle  of  three  events  determines  a 
plane  section  of  the  world,  and  it  is  only  for  that  mode 
of  section  that  the  triangle  is  purely  spatial.  The  propo- 
sition then  expresses  that 

"If  you  measure  with  a  scale  from  A  to  B  and  from 
B  to  C  the  sum  of  your  readings  will  be  greater  than  the 
reading  obtained  by  measuring  with  a  scale  from  A  to  C." 

For  a  time-triangle  the  measurements  must  be  made 
with  an  instrument  which  can  measure  time,  and  the 
proposition  then  expresses  that 

"If  you  measure  with  a  clock  from  A  to  B  and  from 
B  to  C  the  sum  of  your  readings  will  be  less  than  the 
reading  obtained  by  measuring  with  a  clock  from  A  to  C." 

In  order  to  measure  from  an  event  A  to  an  event  B 
with  a  clock  you  must  make  an  adjustment  of  the  clock 
analogous  to  orienting  a  scale  along  the  line  AB.  What 
is  this  analogous  adjustment?  The  purpose  in  either 
case  is  to  bring  both  A  and  B  into  the  immediate 
neighbourhood  of  the  scale  or  clock.  For  the  clock  that 
means  that  after  experiencing  the  event  A  it  must  travel 
with  the  appropriate  velocity  needed  to  reach  the  locality 
of  B  just  at  the  moment  that  B  happens.  Thus  the 
velocity  of  the  clock  is  prescribed.     One  further  point 


TIME  GEOMETRY  135 

should  be  noticed.  After  measuring  with  a  scale  from 
A  to  B  you  can  turn  your  scale  round  and  measure  from 
B  to  A,  obtaining  the  same  result.  But  you  cannot  turn 
a  clock  round,  i.e.  make  it  go  backwards  in  time.  That 
is  important  because  it  decides  which  two  sides  are  less 
than  the  third  side.  If  you  choose  the  wrong  pair  the 
enunciation  of  the  time  proposition  refers  to  an  im- 
possible kind  of  measurement  and  becomes  meaningless. 

You  remember  the  traveller  (p.  39)  who  went  off 
to  a  distant  star  and  returned  absurdly  young.  He  was 
a  clock  measuring  two  sides  of  a  time-triangle.  He 
recorded  less  time  than  the  stay-at-home  observer  who 
was  a  clock  measuring  the  third  side.  Need  I  defend 
my  calling  him  a  clock?  We  are  all  of  us  clocks  whose 
faces  tell  the  passing  years.  This  comparison  was  simply 
an  example  of  the  geometrical  proposition  about  time- 
triangles  (which  in  turn  is  a  particular  case  of  Einstein's 
law  of  longest  track).  The  result  is  quite  explicable  in 
the  ordinary  mechanical  way.  All  the  particles  in  the 
traveller's  body  increase  in  mass  on  account  of  his  high 
velocity  according  to  the  law  already  discussed  and 
verified  by  experiment.  This  renders  them  more  slug- 
gish, and  the  traveller  lives  more  slowly  according  to 
terrestrial  time-reckoning.  However,  the  fact  that  the 
result  is  reasonable  and  explicable  does  not  render  it  the 
less  true  as  a  proposition  of  time  geometry. 

Our  extension  of  geometry  to  include  time  as  well  as 
space  will  not  be  a  simple  addition  of  an  extra  dimension 
to  Euclidean  geometry,  because  the  time  propositions, 
though  analogous,  are  not  identical  with  those  which 
Euclid  has  given  us  for  space  alone.  Actually  the  dif- 
ference between  time  geometry  and  space  geometry  is 
not  very  profound,  and  the  mathematician  easily  glides 
over  it  by  a  discrete  use  of  the  symbol  V-i.     We  still 


i36  GRAVITATION— THE  LAW 

call  (rather  loosely)  the  extended  geometry  Euclidean; 
or,  if  it  is  necessary  to  emphasise  the  distinction,  we 
call  it  hyperbolic  geometry.  The  term  non-Euclidean 
geometry  refers  to  a  more  profound  change,  viz.  that 
involved  in  the  curvature  of  space  and  time  by  which 
we  now  represent  the  phenomenon  of  gravitation.  We 
start  with  Euclidean  geometry  of  space,  and  modify  it 
in  a  comparatively  simple  manner  when  the  time-dimen- 
sion is  added;  but  that  still  leaves  gravitation  to  be 
reckoned  with,  and  wherever  gravitational  effects  are 
observable  it  is  an  indication  that  the  extended  Euclidean 
geometry  is  not  quite  exact,  and  the  true  geometry  is  a 
non-Euclidean  one — appropriate  to  a  curved  region  as 
Euclidean  geometry  is  to  a  flat  region. 

Geometry  and  Mechanics.  The  point  that  deserves  special 
attention  is  that  the  proposition  about  time-triangles  is 
a  statement  as  to  the  behaviour  of  clocks  moving  with 
different  velocities.  We  have  usually  regarded  the 
behaviour  of  clocks  as  coming  under  the  science  of 
mechanics.  We  found  that  it  was  impossible  to  confine 
geometry  to  space  alone,  and  we  had  to  let  it  expand  a 
little.  It  has  expanded  with  a  vengeance  and  taken  a 
big  slice  out  of  mechanics.  There  is  no  stopping  it,  and 
bit  by  bit  geometry  has  now  swallowed  up  the  whole  of 
mechanics.  It  has  also  made  some  tentative  nibbles  at 
electromagnetism.  An  ideal  shines  in  front  of  us,  far 
ahead  perhaps  but  irresistible,  that  the  whole  of  our 
knowledge  of  the  physical  world  may  be  unified  into  a 
single  science  which  will  perhaps  be  expressed  in  terms 
of  geometrical  or  quasi-geometrical  conceptions.  Why 
not?  All  the  knowledge  is  derived  from  measurements 
made  with  various  instruments.  The  instruments  used 
in  the  different  fields  of  inquiry  are  not  fundamentally 


GEOMETRY  AND  MECHANICS  137 

unlike.  There  is  no  reason  to  regard  the  partitions  of 
the  sciences  made  in  the  early  stages  of  human  thought 
as  irremovable. 

But  mechanics  in  becoming  geometry  remains  none 
the  less  mechanics.  The  partition  between  mechanics 
and  geometry  has  broken  down  and  the  nature  of  each 
of  them  has  diffused  through  the  whole.  The  apparent 
supremacy  of  geometry  is  really  due  to  the  fact  that  it 
possesses  the  richer  and  more  adaptable  vocabulary; 
and  since  after  the  amalgamation  we  do  not  need  the 
double  vocabulary  the  terms  employed  are  generally 
taken  from  geometry.  But  besides  the  geometrisation  of 
mechanics  there  has  been  a  mechanisation  of  geometry. 
The  proposition  about  the  space-triangle  quoted  above 
was  seen  to  have  grossly  material  implications  about  the 
behaviour  of  scales  which  would  not  be  realised  by  any- 
one who  thinks  of  it  as  if  it  were  a  proposition  of  pure 
mathematics. 

We  must  rid  our  minds  of  the  idea  that  the  word 
space  in  science  has  anything  to  do  with  void.  As  pre- 
viously explained  it  has  the  other  meaning  of  distance, 
volume,  etc.,  quantities  expressing  physical  measure- 
ment just  as  much  as  force  is  a  quantity  expressing 
physical  measurement.  Thus  the  (rather  crude)  state- 
ment that  Einstein's  theory  reduces  gravitational  force 
to  a  property  of  space  ought  not  to  arouse  misgiving. 
In  any  case  the  physicist  does  not  conceive  of  space 
as  void.  Where  it  is  empty  of  all  else  there  is  still  the 
aether.  Those  who  for  some  reason  dislike  the  word 
aether,  scatter  mathematical  symbols  freely  through  the 
vacuum,  and  I  presume  that  they  must  conceive  some 
kind  of  characteristic  background  for  these  symbols.  I 
do  not  think  any  one  proposes  to  build  even  so  relative 
and  elusive  a  thing  as  force  out  of  entire  nothingness. 


Chapter  VII 

GRAVITATION— THE  EXPLANATION 

The  Law  of  Curvature.  Gravitation  can  be  explained. 
Einstein's  theory  is  not  primarily  an  explanation  of 
gravitation.  When  he  tells  us  that  the  gravitational  field 
corresponds  to  a  curvature  of  space  and  time  he  is  giv- 
ing us  a  picture.  Through  a  picture  we  gain  the  insight 
necessary  to  deduce  the  various  observable  consequences. 
There  remains,  however,  a  further  question  whether 
any  reason  can  be  given  why  the  state  of  things  pictured 
should  exist.  It  is  this  further  inquiry  which  is  meant 
when  we  speak  of  "explaining"  gravitation  in  any  far- 
reaching  sense. 

At  first  sight  the  new  picture  does  not  leave  very 
much  to  explain.  It  shows  us  an  undulating  hum- 
mocky  world,  whereas  a  gravitationless  world  would  be 
plane  and  uniform.  But  surely  a  level  lawn  stands  more 
in  need  of  explanation  than  an  undulating  field,  and  a 
gravitationless  world  would  be  more  difficult  to  account 
for  than  a  world  with  gravitation.  We  are  hardly  called 
upon  to  account  for  a  phenomenon  which  could  only 
be  absent  if  (in  the  building  of  the  world)  express  pre- 
cautions were  taken  to  exclude  it.  If  the  curvature  were 
entirely  arbitrary  this  would  be  the  end  of  the  explana- 
tion; but  there  is  a  law  of  curvature — Einstein's  law  of 
gravitation — and  on  this  law  our  further  inquiry  must 
be  focussed.  Explanation  is  needed  for  regularity,  not 
for  diversity;  and  our  curiosity  is  roused,  not  by  the 
diverse  values  of  the  ten  subsidiary  coefficients  of  curva- 
ture which  differentiate  the  world  from  a  flat  world, 
but  by  the  vanishing  everywhere  of  the  ten  principal 
coefficients. 

138 


THE  LAW  OF  CURVATURE  139 

All  explanations  of  gravitation  on  Newtonian  lines 
have  endeavoured  to  show  why  something  (which  I  have 
disrespectfully  called  a  demon)  is  present  in  the  world. 
An  explanation  on  the  lines  of  Einstein's  theory  must 
show  why  something  (which  we  call  principal  curvature) 
is  excluded  from  the  world. 

In  the  last  chapter  the  law  of  gravitation  was  stated 
in  the  form — the  ten  principal  coefficients  of  curvature 
vanish  in  empty  space.  I  shall  now  restate  it  in  a  slightly 
altered  form — 

The  radius  of  spherical*  curvature  of  every  three-di- 
mensional section  of  the  world,  cut  in  any  direction  at  any 
point  of  empty  space,  is  always  the  same  constant  length. 

Besides  the  alteration  of  form  there  is  actually  a  little 
difference  of  substance  between  the  two  enunciations; 
the  second  corresponds  to  a  later  and,  it  is  believed,  more 
accurate  formula  given  by  Einstein  a  year  or  two  after 
his  first  theory.  The  modification  is. made  necessary  by 
our  realisation  that  space  is  finite  but  unbounded  (p. 
80).  The  second  enunciation  would  be  exactly  equiva- 
lent to  the  first  if  for  "same  constant  length"  we  read 
"infinite  length".  Apart  from  very  speculative  esti- 
mates we  do  not  know  the  constant  length  referred  to, 
but  it  must  certainly  be  greater  than  the  distance  of  the 
furthest  nebula,  say  io20  miles.  A  distinction  between 
so  great  a  length  and  infinite  length  is  unnecessary  in 
most  of  our  arguments  and  investigations,  but  it  is 
necessary  in  the  present  chapter. 

♦Cylindrical  curvature  of  the  world  has  nothing  to  do  with  gravita- 
tion, nor  so  far  as  we  know  with  any  other  phenomenon.  Anything 
drawn  on  the  surface  of  a  cylinder  can  be  unrolled  into  a  flat  map  without 
distortion,  but  the  curvature  introduced  in  the  last  chapter  was  intended 
to  account  for  the  distortion  which  appears  in  our  customary  flat  map;  it 
is  therefore  curvature  of  the  type  exemplified  by  a  sphere,  not  a  cylinder. 


140         GRAVITATION— THE  EXPLANATION 

We  must  try  to  reach  the  vivid  significance  which 
lies  behind  the  obscure  phraseology  of  the  law.  Suppose 
that  you  are  ordering  a  concave  mirror  for  a  telescope. 
In  order  to  obtain  what  you  want  you  will  have  to 
specify  two  lengths  (i)  the  aperture,  and  (2)  the  radius 
of  curvature.  These  lengths  both  belong  to  the  mirror — 
both  are  necessary  to  describe  the  kind  of  mirror  you 
want  to  purchase — but  they  belong  to  it  in  different 
ways.  You  may  order  a  mirror  of  100  foot  radius  of 
curvature  and  yet  receive  it  by  parcel  post.  In  a  certain 
sense  the  100  foot  length  travels  with  the  mirror,  but 
it  does  so  in  a  way  outside  the  cognizance  of  the  postal 
authorities.  The  100  foot  length  belongs  especially  to 
the  surface  of  the  mirror,  a  two-dimensional  continuum; 
space-time  is  a  four-dimensional  continuum,  and  you  will 
see  from  this  analogy  that  there  can  be  lengths  belonging 
in  this  way  to  a  chunk  of  space-time — lengths  having 
nothing  to  do  with  the  largeness  or  smallness  of  the 
chunk,  but  none  the  less  part  of  the  specification  of  the 
particular  sample.  Owing  to  the  two  extra  dimensions 
there  are  many  more  such  lengths  associated  with  space- 
time  than  with  the  mirror  surface.  In  particular,  there 
is  not  only  one  general  radius  of  spherical  curvature,  but 
a  radius  corresponding  to  any  direction  you  like  to  take. 
For  brevity  I  will  call  this  the  "directed  radius"  of  the 
world.  Suppose  now  that  you  order  a  chunk  of  space- 
time  with  a  directed  radius  of  500  trillion  miles  in  one 
direction  and  800  trillion  miles  in  another.  Nature 
replies  "No.  We  do  not  stock  that.  We  keep  a  wide 
range  of  choice  as  regards  other  details  of  specification; 
but  as  regards  directed  radius  we  have  nothing  different 
in  different  directions,  and  in  fact  all  our  goods  have  the 
one  standard  radius,  x  trillion  miles."  I  cannot  tell  you 
what  number  to  put  for  x  because  that  is  still  a  secret 
of  the  firm. 


RELATIVITY  OF  LENGTH  141 

The  fact  that  this  directed  radius  which,  one  would 
think,  might  so  easily  differ  from  point  to  point  and 
from  direction  to  direction,  has  only  one  standard  value 
in  the  world  is  Einstein's  law  of  gravitation.  From  it 
we  can  by  rigorous  mathematical  deduction  work  out  the 
motions  of  planets  and  predict,  for  example,  the  eclipses 
of  the  next  thousand  years;  for,  as  already  explained, 
the  law  of  gravitation  includes  also  the  law  of  motion. 
Newton's  law  of  gravitation  is  an  approximate  adapta- 
tion of  it  for  practical  calculation.  Building  up  from 
the  law  all  is  clear;  but  what  lies  beneath  it?  Why  is 
there  this  unexpected  standardisation?  That  is  what  we 
must  now  inquire  into. 

Relativity  of  Length.  There  is  no  such  thing  as  absolute 
length;  we  can  only  express  the  length  of  one  thing  in 
terms  of  the  length  of  something  else.*  And  so  when 
we  speak  of  the  length  of  the  directed  radius  we  mean 
its  length  compared  with  the  standard  metre  scale. 
Moreover,  to  make  this  comparison,  the  two  lengths 
must  lie  alongside.  Comparison  at  a  distance  is  as  un- 
thinkable as  action  at  a  distance;  more  so,  because  com- 
parison is  a  less  vague  conception  than  action.  We  must 
either  convey  the  standard  metre  to  the  site  of  the 
length  we  are  measuring,  or  we  must  use  some  device 
which,  we  are  satisfied,  will  give  the  same  result  as  if  we 
actually  moved  the  metre  rod. 

Now  if  we  transfer  the  metre  rod  to  another  point  of 
space  and  time,  does  it  necessarily  remain  a  metre  long? 
Yes,  of  course  it  does;  so  long  as  it  is  the  standard  of 
length  it  cannot  be  anything  else  but  a  metre.  But  does 
it  really  remain  the  metre  that  it  was?     I  do  not  know 

*  This  relativity  with  respect  to  a  standard  unit  is,  of  course,  addi- 
tional to  and  independent  of  the  relativity  with  respect  to  the  observer's 
motion  treated  in  chapter  n. 


1 42         GRAVITATION— THE  EXPLANATION 

what  you  mean  by  the  question;  there  is  nothing  by 
reference  to  which  we  could  expose  delinquencies  of  the 
standard  rod,  nothing  by  reference  to  which  we  could 
conceive  the  nature  of  the  supposed  delinquencies.  Still 
the  standard  rod  was  chosen  with  considerable  care;  its 
material  was  selected  to  fulfil  certain  conditions — to  be 
affected  as  little  as  possible  by  casual  influences  such 
as  temperature,  strain  or  corrosion,  in  order  that  its 
extension  might  depend  only  on  the  most  essential  char- 
acteristics of  its  surroundings,  present  and  past.*  We 
cannot  say  that  it  was  chosen  to  keep  the  same  absolute 
length  since  there   is  no  such  thing  known;  but  it  was 

*  In  so  far  as  these  casual  influences  are  not  entirely  eliminated  by 
the  selection  of  material  and  the  precautions  in  using  the  rod,  appropriate 
corrections  must  be  applied.  But  the  rod  must  not  be  corrected  for 
essential  characteristics  of  the  space  it  is  measuring.  We  correct  the 
reading  of  a  voltmeter  for  temperature,  but  it  would  be  nonsensical  to 
correct  it  for  effects  of  the  applied  voltage.  The  distinction  between 
casual  and  essential  influences — those  to  be  eliminated  and  those  to  be 
left  in — depends  on  the  intention  of  the  measurements.  The  measuring 
rod  is  intended  for  surveying  space,  and  the  essential  characteristic  of 
space  is  "metric".  It  would  be  absurd  to  correct  the  readings  of  our 
scale  to  the  values  they  would  have  had  if  the  space  had  some  other 
metric.  The  region  of  the  world  to  which  the  metric  refers  may  also 
contain  an  electric  field;  this  will  be  regarded  as  a  casual  characteristic 
since  the  measuring  rod  is  not  intended  for  surveying  electric  fields. 
I  do  not  mean  that  from  a  broader  standpoint  the  electric  field  is  any  less 
essential  to  the  region  than  its  peculiar  metric.  It  would  be  hard  to  say 
in  what  sense  it  would  remain  the  same  region  if  any  of  its  qualities  were 
other  than  they  actually  are.  This  point  does  not  trouble  us  here,  because 
there  are  vast  regions  of  the  world  practically  empty  of  all  characteristics 
except  metric,  and  it  is  to  these  that  the  law  of  gravitation  is  applied  both 
in  theory  and  in  practice.  It  has  seemed,  however,  desirable  to  dwell  on 
this  distinction  between  essential  and  casual  characteristics  because  there 
are  some  who,  knowing  that  we  cannot  avoid  in  all  circumstances  cor- 
rections for  casual  influences,  regard  that  as  license  to  adopt  any  arbi- 
trary system  of  corrections — a  procedure  which  would  merely  have  the 
effect  of  concealing  what  the  measures  can  teach  us  about  essential 
characteristics. 


RELATIVITY  OF  LENGTH  143 

chosen  so  that  it  might  not  be  prevented  by  casual  in- 
fluences from  keeping  the  same  relative  length — relative 
to  what?  Relative  to  some  length  inalienably  associated 
with  the  region  in  which  it  is  placed.  I  can  conceive 
of  no  other  answer.  An  example  of  such  a  length 
inalienably  associated  with  a  region  is  the  directed  radius. 

The  long  and  short  of  it  is  that  when  the  standard 
metre  takes  up  a  new  position  or  direction  it  measures 
itself  against  the  directed  radius  of  the  world  in  that 
region  and  direction,  and  takes  up  an  extension  which 
is  a  definite  fraction  of  the  directed  radius.  I  do  not 
see  what  else  it  could  do.  We  picture  the  rod  a  little 
bewildered  in  its  new  surroundings  wondering  how 
large  it  ought  to  be — how  much  of  the  unfamiliar  terri- 
tory its  boundaries  ought  to  take  in.  It  wants  to  do 
just  what  it  did  before.  Recollections  of  the  chunk  of 
space  that  it  formerly  filled  do  not  help,  because  there 
is  nothing  of  the  nature  of  a  landmark.  The  one  thing 
it  can  recognise  is  a  directed  length  belonging  to  the 
region  where  it  finds  itself;  so  it  makes  itself  the  same 
fraction  of  this  directed  length  as  it  did  before. 

If  the  standard  metre  is  always  the  same  fraction  of 
the  directed  radius,  the  directed  radius  is  always  the 
same  number  of  metres.  Accordingly  the  directed 
radius  is  made  out  to  have  the  same  length  for  all 
positions  and  directions.  Hence  we  have  the  law  of 
gravitation. 

When  we  felt  surprise  at  finding  as  a  law  of  Nature 
that  the  directed  radius  of  curvature  was  the  same  for 
all  positions  and  directions,  we  did  not  realise  that  our 
unit  of  length  had  already  made  itself  a  constant  fraction 
of  the  directed  radius.  The  whole  thing  is  a  vicious 
circle.    The  law  of  gravitation  is — a  put-up  job. 


144         GRAVITATION— THE  EXPLANATION 

This  explanation  introduces  no  new  hypothesis.  In 
saying  that  a  material  system  of  standard  specification 
always  occupies  a  constant  fraction  of  the  directed  radius 
of  the  region  where  it  is,  we  are  simply  reiterating 
Einstein's  law  of  gravitation — stating  it  in  the  inverse 
form.  Leaving  aside  for  the  moment  the  question 
whether  this  behaviour  of  the  rod  is  to  be  expected  or 
not,  the  law  of  gravitation  assures  us  that  that  is  the 
behaviour.  To  see  the  force  of  the  explanation  we 
must,  however,  realise  the  relativity  of  extension.  Exten- 
sion which  is  not  relative  to  something  in  the  surround- 
ings has  no  meaning.  Imagine  yourself  alone  in  the 
midst  of  nothingness,  and  then  try  to  tell  me  how  large 
you  are.  The  definiteness  of  extension  of  the  standard 
rod  can  only  be  a  definiteness  of  its  ratio  to  some  other 
extension.  But  we  are  speaking  now  of  the  extension 
of  a  rod  placed  in  empty  space,  so  that  every  standard 
of  reference  has  been  removed  except  extensions  be- 
longing to  and  implied  by  the  metric  of  the  region.  It 
follows  that  one  such  extension  must  appear  from  our 
measurements  to  be  constant  everywhere  (homogeneous 
and  isotropic)  on  account  of  its  constant  relation  to  what 
we  have  accepted  as  the  unit  of  length. 

We  approached  the  problem  from  the  point  of  view 
that  the  actual  world  with  its  ten  vanishing  coefficients 
of  curvature  (or  its  isotropic  directed  curvature)  has  a 
specialisation  which  requires  explanation;  we  were  then 
comparing  it  in  our  minds  with  a  world  suggested  by 
the  pure  mathematician  which  has  entirely  arbitrary 
curvature.  But  the  fact  is  that  a  world  of  arbitrary 
curvature  is  a  sheer  impossibility.  If  not  the  directed 
radius,  then  some  other  directed  length  derivable  from 
the  metric,  is  bound  to  be  homogeneous  and  isotropic. 
In   applying   the   ideas   of   the   pure    mathematician  we 


RELATIVITY  OF  LENGTH  145 

overlooked  the  fact  that  he  was  imagining  a  world 
surveyed  from  outside  with  standards  foreign  to  it 
whereas  we  have  to  do  with  a  world  surveyed  from 
within  with  standards  conformable  to  it. 

The  explanation  of  the  law  of  gravitation  thus  lies  in 
the  fact  that  we  are  dealing  with  a  world  surveyed  from 
within.  From  this  broader  standpoint  the  foregoing 
argument  can  be  generalised  so  that  it  applies  not  only 
to  a  survey  with  metre  rods  but  to  a  survey  by  optical 
methods,  which  in  practice  are  generally  substituted  as 
equivalent.  When  we  recollect  that  surveying  apparatus 
can  have  no  extension  in  itself  but  only  in  relation  to  the 
world,  so  that  a  survey  of  space  is  virtually  a  self-com- 
parison of  space,  it  is  perhaps  surprising  that  such  a 
self-comparison  should  be  able  to  show  up  any  hetero- 
geneity at  all.  It  can  in  fact  be  proved  that  the  metric 
of  a  two-dimensional  or  a  three-dimensional  world  sur- 
veyed from  within  is  necessarily  uniform.  With  four  or 
more  dimensions  heterogeneity  becomes  possible,  but  it 
is  a  heterogeneity  limited  by  a  law  which  imposes  some 
measure  of  homogeneity. 

I  believe  that  this  has  a  close  bearing  on  the  rather 
heterodox  views  of  Dr.  Whitehead  on  relativity.  He 
breaks  away  from  Einstein  because  he  will  not  admit 
the  non-uniformity  of  space-time  involved  in  Einstein's 
theory.  "I  deduce  that  our  experience  requires  and 
exhibits  a  basis  of  uniformity,  and  that  in  the  case  of 
nature  this  basis  exhibits  itself  as  the  uniformity  of 
spatio-temporal  relations.  This  conclusion  entirely  cuts 
away  the  casual  heterogeneity  of  these  relations  which 
is  the  essential  of  Einstein's  later  theory."*  But  we  now 
see  that  Einstein's  theory  asserts  a  casual  heterogeneity 

*A.  N.  Whitehead,  The  Principle  of  Relativity,  Preface. 


146         GRAVITATION—THE  EXPLANATION 

of  only  one  set  of  ten  coefficients  and  complete  uniform- 
ity of  the  other  ten.  It  therefore  does  not  leave  us  with- 
out the  basis  of  uniformity  of  which  Whitehead  in  his 
own  way  perceived  the  necessity.  Moreover,  this  uni- 
formity is  not  the  result  of  a  law  casually  imposed  on  the 
world;  it  is  inseparable  from  the  conception  of  survey  of 
the  world  from  within — which  is,  I  think,  just  the  con- 
dition that  Whitehead  would  demand.  If  the  world  of 
space-time  had  been  of  two  or  of  three  dimensions 
Whitehead  would  have  been  entirely  right;  but  then 
there  could  have  been  no  Einstein  theory  of  gravitation 
for  him  to  criticise.  Space-time  being  four-dimensional, 
we  must  conclude  that  Whitehead  discovered  an  im- 
portant truth  about  uniformity  but  misapplied  it. 

The  conclusion  that  the  extension  of  an  object  in  any 
direction  in  the  four-dimensional  world  is  determined  by 
comparison  with  the  radius  of  curvature  in  that  direction 
has  one  curious  consequence.  So  long  as  the  direction 
in  the  four-dimensional  world  is  space-like,  no  difficulty 
arises.  But  when  we  pass  over  to  time-like  directions 
(within  the  cone  of  absolute  past  or  future)  the  directed 
radius  is  an  imaginary  length.  Unless  the  object 
ignores  the  warning  symbol  V  —  i  it  has  no  standard 
of  reference  for  settling  its  time  extension.  It  has  no 
standard  duration.  An  electron  decides  how  large  it 
ought  to  be  by  measuring  itself  against  the  radius  of 
the  world  in  its  space-directions.  It  cannot  decide  how 
long  it  ought  to  exist  because  there  is  no  real  radius  of 
the  world  in  its  time-direction.  Therefore  it  just  goes  on 
existing  indefinitely.  This  is  not  intended  to  be  a  rigor- 
ous proof  of  the  immortality  of  the  electron — subject 
always  to  the  condition  imposed  throughout  these 
arguments  that  no  agency  other  than  metric  interferes 
with   the    extension.      But    it   shows    that    the    electron 


PREDICTIONS  FROM  THE  LAW  147 

behaves  in  the  simple  way  which  we  might  at  least  hope 
to  find.* 

Predictions  from  the  Law.  I  suppose  that  it  is  at  first 
rather  staggering  to  find  a  law  supposed  to  control  the 
movements  of  stars  and  planets  turned  into  a  law 
finicking  with  the  behaviour  of  measuring  rods.  But 
there  is  no  prediction  made  by  the  law  of  gravitation  in 
which  the  behaviour  of  measuring  appliances  does  not 
play  an  essential  part.  A  typical  prediction  from  the  law 
is  that  pn  a  certain  date  384,400,000  metre  rods  laid 
end  to  end  would  stretch  from  the  earth  to  the  moon. 
We  may  use  more  circumlocutory  language,  but  that  is 
what  is  meant.  The  fact  that  in  testing  the  prediction 
we  shall  trust  to  indirect  evidence,  not  carrying  out  the 
whole  operation  literally,  is  not  relevant;  the  prophecy 
is  made  in  good  faith  and  not  with  the  intention  of  tak- 
ing advantage  of  our  remissness  in  checking  it. 

We  have  condemned  the  law  of  gravitation  as  a  put- 
up  job.  You  will  want  to  know  how  after  such  a  dis- 
creditable exposure  it  can  still  claim  to  predict  eclipses 
and  other  events  which  come  off. 

A  famous  philosopher  has  said — 

"The  stars  are  not  pulled  this  way  and  that  by 
mechanical  forces;  theirs  is  a  free  motion.  They  go  on 
their  way,  as  the  ancients  said,  like  the  blessed  gods."  f 

This  sounds  particularly  foolish  even  for  a  philo- 
sopher; but  I  believe  that  there  is  a  sense  in  which  it  is 
true. 

*  On  the  other  hand  a  quantum  (see  chapter  ix)  has  a  definite 
periodicity  associated  with  it,  so  that  it  must  be  able  to  measure  itself 
against  a  time-extension.  Anyone  who  contemplates  the  mathematical 
equations  of  the  new  quantum  theory  will  see  abundant  evidence  of  the 
battle  with  the  intervening  symbol   V — *• 

t  Hegel,  Werke  (1842  Ed.),  Bd.  7,  Abt.  1,  p.  97. 


i48         GRAVITATION— THE  EXPLANATION 

We  have  already  had  three  versions  of  what  the  earth 
is  trying  to  do  when  it  describes  its  elliptic  orbit  around 
the  sun. 

(i)  It  is  trying  to  go  in  a  straight  line  but  it  is 
roughly  pulled  away  by  a  tug  emanating  from  the  sun. 

(2)  It  is  taking  the  longest  possible  route  through 
the  curved  space-time  around  the  sun. 

(3)  It  is  accommodating  its  track  so  as  to  avoid 
causing  any  illegal  kind  of  curvature  in  the  empty  space 
around  it. 

We  now  add  a  fourth  version. 

(4)  The  earth  goes  anyhow  it  likes. 

It  is  not  a  long  step  from  the  third  version  to  the 
fourth  now  that  we  have  seen  that  the  mathematical 
picture  of  empty  space  containing  "illegal"  curvature 
is  a  sheer  impossibility  in  a  world  surveyed  from  within. 
For  if  illegal  curvature  is  a  sheer  impossibility  the  earth 
will  not  have  to  take  any  special  precautions  to  avoid 
causing  it,  and  can  do  anything  it  likes.  And  yet  the 
non-occurrence  of  this  impossible  curvature  is  the  law 
(of  gravitation)  by  which  we  calculate  the  track  of  the 
earth! 

The  key  to  the  paradox  is  that  we  ourselves,  our 
conventions,  the  kind  of  thing  that  attracts  our  interest, 
are  much  more  concerned  than  we  realise  in  any  account 
we  give  of  how  the  objects  of  the  physical  world  are 
behaving.  And  so  an  object  which,  viewed  through  our 
frame  of  conventions,  anay  seem  to  be  behaving  in  a 
very  special  and  remarkable  way  may,  viewed  according 
to  another  set  of  conventions,  be  doing  nothing  to  excite 
particular  comment.  This  will  be  clearer  if  we  consider 
a  practical  illustration,  and  at  the  same  time  defend 
version    (4). 


PREDICTIONS  FROM  THE  LAW  149 

You  will  say  that  the  earth  must  certainly  get  into 
the  right  position  for  the  eclipse  next  June  (1927);  so 
it  cannot  be  free  to  go  anywhere  it  pleases.  I  can  put 
that  right.  I  hold  to  it  that  the  earth  goes  anywhere  it 
pleases.  The  next  thing  is  that  we  must  find  out  where 
it  has  been  pleased  to  go.  The  important  question  for  us 
is  not  where  the  earth  has  got  to  in  the  inscrutable 
absolute  behind  the  phenomena,  but  where  we  shall 
locate  it  in  our  conventional  background  of  space  and 
time.     We  must  take  measurements  of  its  position,  for 


Fig.  6 

example,  measurements  of  its  distance  from  the  sun. 
In  Fig.  6,  SSx  shows  the  ridge  in  the  world  which  we 
recognise  as  the  sun;  I  have  drawn  the  earth's  ridge  in 
duplicate  (EE1}  EE2)  because  I  imagine  it  as  still  un- 
decided which  track  it  will  take.  If  it  takes  EE±  we  lay 
our  measuring  rods  end  to  end  down  the  ridges  and 
across  the  valley  from  S±  to  E±,  count  up  the  number, 
and  report  the  result  as  the  earth's  distance  from  the 
sun.  The  measuring  rods,  you  will  remember,  adjust 
their  lengths  proportionately  to  the  radius  of  curvature 
of  the  world.    The  curvature  along  this  contour  is  rather 


150         GRAVITATION— THE  EXPLANATION 

large  and  the  radius  of  curvature  small.  The  rods 
therefore  are  small,  and  there  will  be  more  of  them  in 
$i£i  than  the  picture  would  lead  you  to  expect.  If  the 
earth  chooses  to  go  to  E2  the  curvature  is  less  sharp; 
the  greater  radius  of  curvature  implies  greater  length 
of  the  rods.  The  number  needed  to  stretch  from  S±  to 
E2  will  not  be  so  great  as  the  diagram  at  first  suggests; 
it  will  not  be  increased  in  anything  like  the  proportion 
of  S±E2  to  S±EX  in  the  figure.  We  should  not  be  sur- 
prised if  the  number  turned  out  to  be  the  same  in  both 
cases.  If  so,  the  surveyor  will  report  the  same  distance 
of  the  earth  from  the  sun  whether  the  track  is  EE±  or 
EE2.  And  the  Superintendent  of  the  Nautical  Almanac 
who  published  this  same  distance  some  years  in  advance 
will  claim  that  he  correctly  predicted  where  the  earth 
would  go. 

And  so  you  see  that  the  earth  can  play  truant  to  any 
extent  but  our  measurements  will  still  report  it  in  the 
place  assigned  to  it  by  the  Nautical  Almanac.  The 
predictions  of  that  authority  pay  no  attention  to  the 
vagaries  of  the  god-like  earth;  they  are  based  on  what 
will  happen  when  we  come  to  measure  up  the  path  that 
it  has  chosen.  We  shall  measure  it  with  rods  that  adjust 
themselves  to  the  curvature  of  the  world.  The  mathe- 
matical expression  of  this  fact  is  the  law  of  gravitation 
used  in  the  predictions. 

Perhaps  you  will  object  that  astronomers  do  not  in 
practice  lay  measuring  rods  end  to  end  through  inter- 
planetary space  in  order  to  find  out  where  the  planets 
are.  Actually  the  position  is  deduced  from  the  light 
rays.  But  the  light  as  it  proceeds  has  to  find  out  what 
course  to  take  in  order  to  go  "straight",  in  much  the 
same  way  as  the  metre  rod  has  to  find  out  how  far  to 
extend.     The  metric  or  curvature  is  a  sign-post  for  the 


PREDICTIONS  FROM  THE  LAW  151 

light  as  it  is  a  gauge  for  the  rod.  The  light  track  is  in 
fact  controlled  by  the  curvature  in  such  a  way  that  it  is 
incapable  of  exposing  the  sham  law  of  curvature.  And 
so  wherever  the  sun,  moon  and  earth  may  have  got  to, 
the  light  will  not  give  them  away.  If  the  law  of  curva- 
ture predicts  an  eclipse  the  light  will  take  such  a  track 
that  there  is  an  eclipse.  The  law  of  gravitation  is  not  a 
stern  ruler  controlling  the  heavenly  bodies;  it  is  a  kind- 
hearted  accomplice  who  covers  up  their  delinquencies. 

I  do  not  recommend  you  to  try  to  verify  from  Fig.  6 
that  the  number  of  rods  in  SiEt  (full  line)  and  SJL2 
(dotted  line)  is  the  same.  There  are  two  dimensions  of 
space-time  omitted  in  the  picture  besides  the  extra  dimen- 
sions in  which  space-time  must  be  supposed  to  be  bent; 
moreover  it  is  the  spherical,  not  the  cylindrical,  curvature 
which  is  ,the  gauge  for  the  length.  It  might  be  an 
instructive,  though  very  laborious,  task  to  make  this 
direct  verification,  but  we  know  beforehand  that  the 
measured  distance  of  the  earth  from  the  sun  must  be 
the  same  for  either  track.  The  law  of  gravitation,  ex- 
pressed mathematically  by  G^u  —  Xg^t  means  nothing 
more  nor  less  than  that  the  unit  of  length  everywhere 
is  a  constant  fraction  of  the  directed  radius  of  the  world 
at  that  point.  And  as  the  astronomer  who  predicts  the 
future  position  of  the  earth  does  not  assume  anything 
more  about  what  the  earth  will  choose  to  do  than  is 
expressed  in  the  law  GtLV^=Xglxl/i  so  we  shall  find  the 
same  position  of  the  earth,  if  we  assume  nothing  more 
than  that  the  practical  unit  of  length  involved  in  measure- 
ments of  the  position  is  a  constant  fraction  of  the  directed 
radius.  We  do  not  need  to  decide  whether  the  track  is 
to  be  represented  by  EE±  or  EE2,  and  it  would  convey 
no  information  as  to  any  observable  phenomena  if  we 
knew  the  representation. 


152         GRAVITATION— THE  EXPLANATION 

I  shall  have  to  emphasise  elsewhere  that  the  whole  of 
our  physical  knowledge  is  based  on  measures  and  that 
the  physical  world  consists,  so  to  speak,  of  measure- 
groups  resting  on  a  shadowy  background  that  lies 
outside  the  scope  of  physics.  Therefore  in  conceiving 
a  world  which  had  existence  apart  from  the  measure- 
ments that  we  make  of  it,  I  was  trespassing  outside  the 
limits  of  what  we  call  physical  reality.  I  would  not 
dissent  from  the  view  that  a  vagary  which  by  its  very 
nature  could  not  be  measurable  has  no  claim  to  a  physical 
existence.  No  one  knows  what  is  meant  by  such  a 
vagary.  I  said  that  the  earth  might  go  anywhere  it 
chose,  but  did  not  provide  a  "where"  for  it  to  choose; 
since  our  conception  of  "where"  is  based  on  space 
measurements  which  were  at  that  stage  excluded.  But 
I  do  not  think  I  have  been  illogical.  I  am  urging  that, 
do  what  it  will,  the  earth  cannot  get  out  of  the  track 
laid  down  for  it  by  the  law  of  gravitation.  In  order  to 
show  this  I  must  suppose  that  the  earth  has  made  the 
attempt  and  stolen  nearer  to  the  sun;  then  I  show  that 
our  measures  conspire  quietly  to  locate  it  back  in  its 
proper  orbit.  I  have  to  admit  in  the  end  that  the  earth 
never  was  out  of  its  proper  orbit;*  I  do  not  mind  that, 
because  meanwhile  I  have  proved  my  point.  The  fact 
that  a  predictable  path  through  space  and  time  is  laid 
down  for  the  earth  is  not  a  genuine  restriction  on  its 
conduct,  but  is  imposed  by  the  formal  scheme  in  which 
we  draw  up  our  account  of  its  conduct. 

*  Because  I  can  attach  no  meaning  to  an  orbit  other  than  an  orbit  in 
space  and  time,  i.e.  as  located  by  measures.  But  I  could  not  assume  that 
the  alternative  orbit  would  be  meaningless  (inconsistent  with  possible 
measures)   until  I  tried  it. 


NON-EMPTY  SPACE  153 

Non-Empty  Space.  The  law  that  the  directed  radius  is 
constant  does  not  apply  to  space  which  is  not  completely 
empty.  There  is  no  longer  any  reason  to  expect  it  to 
hold.  The  statement  that  the  region  is  not  empty  means 
that  it  has  other  characteristics  besides  metric,  and  the 
metre  rod  can  then  find  other  lengths  besides  curvatures 
to  measure  itself  against.  Referring  to  the  earlier  (suf- 
ficiently approximate)  expression  of  the  law,  the  ten 
principal  coefficients  of  curvature  are  zero  in  empty 
space  but  have  non-zero  values  in  non-empty  space.  It 
is  therefore  natural  to  use  these  coefficients  as  a  measure 
of  the  fullness  of  space. 

One  of  the  coefficients  corresponds  to  mass  (or 
energy)  and  in  most  practical  cases  it  outweighs  the 
others  in  importance.  The  old  definition  of  mass  as 
"quantity  of  matter"  associates  it  with  a  fullness  of 
space.  Three  other  coefficients  make  up  the  momentum 
— a  directed  quantity  with  three  independent  com- 
ponents. The  remaining  six  coefficients  of  principal 
curvature  make  up  the  stress  or  pressure-system.  Mass, 
momentum  and  stress  accordingly  represent  the  non- 
emptiness  of  a  region  in  so  far  as  it  is  able  to  disturb 
the  usual  surveying  apparatus  with  which  we  explore 
space — clocks,  scales,  light-rays,  etc.  It  should  be 
added,  however,  that  this  is  a  summary  description  and 
not  a  full  account  of  the  non-emptiness,  because  we 
have  other  exploring  apparatus — magnets,  electroscopes, 
etc. — which  provide  further  details.  It  is  usually  con- 
sidered that  when  we  use  these  we  are  exploring  not 
space,  but  a  field  in  space.  The  distinction  thus  created 
is  a  rather  artificial  one  which  is  unlikely  to  be  accepted 
permanently.  It  would  seem  that  the  results  of  ex- 
ploring the  world  with  a  measuring  scale  and  a  magnetic 
compass  respectively  ought  to  be  welded  together  into 


154         GRAVITATION— THE  EXPLANATION 

a  unified  description,  just  as  we  have  welded  together 
results  of  exploration  with  a  scale  and  a  clock.  Some 
progress  has  been  made  towards  this  unification.  There 
is,  however,  a  real  reason  for  admitting  a  partially 
separate  treatment;  the  one  mode  of  exploration  deter- 
mines the  symmetrical  properties  and  the  other  the 
antisymmetrical  properties  of  the  underlying  world- 
structure.* 

Objection  has  often  been  taken,  especially  by  philo- 
sophical writers,  to  the  crudeness  of  Einstein's  initial 
requisitions,  viz.  a  clock  and  a  measuring  scale.  But  the 
body  of  experimental  knowledge  of  the  world  which 
Einstein's  theory  seeks  to  set  in  order  has  not  come  into 
our  minds  as  a  heaven-sent  inspiration;  it  is  the  result 
of  a  survey  in  which  the  clock  and  the  scale  have  actually 
played  the  leading  part.  They  may  seem  very  gross 
instruments  to  those  accustomed  to  the  conceptions  of 
atoms  and  electrons,  but  it  is  correspondingly  gross 
knowledge  that  we  have  been  discussing  in  the  chapters 
concerned  with  Einstein's  theory.  As  the  relativity 
theory  develops,  it  is  generally  found  desirable  to  replace 
the  clock  and  scale  by  the  moving  particle  and  light- 
ray  as  the  primary  surveying  appliances;  these  are  test 
bodies  of  simpler  structure.  But  they  are  still  gross 
compared  with  atomic  phenomena.  The  light-ray,  for 
instance,  is  not  applicable  to  measurements  so  refined 
that  the  diffraction  of  light  must  be  taken  into  account. 
Our  knowledge  of  the  external  world  cannot  be  divorced 
from  the  nature  of  the  appliances  with  which  we  have 
obtained  the  knowledge.  The  truth  of  the  law  of  gravi- 
tation cannot  be  regarded  as  subsisting  apart  from  the 
experimental  procedure  by  which  we  have  ascertained 
its  truth. 

*  See  p.  236. 


NON-EMPTY  SPACE  155 

The  conception  of  frames  of  space  and  time,  and  of  the 
non-emptiness  of  the  world  described  as  energy,  momen- 
tum, etc.,  is  bound  up  with  the  survey  by  gross  ap- 
pliances. When  they  can  no  longer  be  supported  by 
such  a  survey,  the  conceptions  melt  away  into  meaning- 
lessness.  In  particular  the  interior  of  the  atom  could 
not  conceivably  be  explored  by  a  gross  survey.  We 
cannot  put  a  clock  or  a  scale  into  the  interior  of  an  atom. 
It  cannot  be  too  strongly  insisted  that  the  terms  dis- 
tance, period  of  time,  mass,  energy,  momentum,  etc., 
cannot  be  used  in  a  description  of  an  atom  with  the 
same  meanings  that  they  have  in  our  gross  experience. 
The  atomic  physicist  who  uses  these  terms  must  find 
his  own  meanings  for  them — must  state  the  appliances 
which  he  requisitions  when  he  imagines  them  to  be 
measured.  It  is  sometimes  supposed  that  (in  addition 
to  electrical  forces)  there  is  a  minute  gravitational 
attraction  between  an  atomic  nucleus  and  the  satellite 
electrons,  obeying  the  same  law  as  the  gravitation 
between  the  sun  and  its  planets.  The  supposition  seems 
to  me  fantastic;  but  it  is  impossible  to  discuss  it  without 
any  indication  as  to  how  the  region  within  the  atom  is 
supposed  to  have  been  measured  up.  Apart  from  such 
measuring  up  the  electron  goes  as  it  pleases  "like  the 
blessed  gods". 

We  have  reached  a  point  of  great  scientific  and  philo- 
sophic interest.  The  ten  principal  coefficients  of  cur- 
vature of  the  world  are  not  strangers  to  us;  they  are 
already  familiar  in  scientific  discussion  under  other 
names  (energy,  momentum,  stress).  This  is  comparable 
with  a  famous  turning-point  in  the  development  of  elec- 
tromagnetic theory.  The  progress  of  the  subject  led  to 
the  consideration  of  waves  of  electric  and  magnetic  force 
travelling    through    the    aether;    then    it    flashed    upon 


156         GRAVITATION— THE  EXPLANATION 

Maxwell  that  these  waves  were  not  strangers  but  were 
already  familiar  in  our  experience  under  the  name  of 
light.  The  method  of  identification  is  the  same.  It  is 
calculated  that  electromagnetic  waves  will  have  just 
those  properties  which  light  is  observed  to  have;  so  too 
it  is  calculated  that  the  ten  coefficients  of  curvature  have 
just  those  properties  which  energy,  momentum  and  stress 
are  observed  to  have.  We  refer  here  to  physical  pro- 
perties only.  No  physical  theory  is  expected  to  explain 
why  there  is  a  particular  kind  of  image  in  our  minds 
associated  with  light,  nor  why  a  conception  of  substance 
has  arisen  in  our  minds  in  connection  with  those  parts 
of  the  world  containing  mass. 

This  leads  to  a  considerable  simplification,  because 
identity  replaces  causation.  On  the  Newtonian  theory 
no  explanation  of  gravitation  would  be  considered  com- 
plete unless  it  described  the  mechanism  by  which  a  piece 
of  matter  gets  a  grip  on  the  surrounding  medium  and 
makes  it  the  carrier  of  the  gravitational  influence  radi- 
ating from  the  matter.  Nothing  corresponding  to  this 
is  required  in  the  present  theory.  We  do  not  ask  how 
mass  gets  a  grip  on  space-time  and  causes  the  curvature 
which  our  theory  postulates.  That  would  be  as  super- 
fluous as  to  ask  how  light  gets  a  grip  on  the  electro- 
magnetic medium  so  as  to  cause  it  to  oscillate.  The 
light  is  the  oscillation;  the  mass  is  the  curvature.  There 
is  no  causal  effect  to  be  attributed  to  mass;  still  less  is 
there  any  to  be  attributed  to  matter.  The  conception 
of  matter,  which  we  associate  with  these  regions  of  un- 
usual contortion,  is  a  monument  erected  by  the  mind  to 
mark  the  scene  of  conflict.  When  you  visit  the  site  of  a 
battle,  do  you  ever  ask  how  the  monument  that  com- 
memorates it  can  have  caused  so  much  carnage? 

The   philosophic    outcome    of    this    identification    will 


NON-EUCLIDEAN  GEOMETRY  157 

occupy  us  considerably  in  later  chapters.  Before  leaving 
the  subject  of  gravitation  I  wish  to  say  a  little  about 
the  meaning  of  space-curvature  and  non-Euclidean 
geometry. 

Non-Euclidean  Geometry.  I  have  been  encouraging  you 
to  think  of  space-time  as  curved;  but  I  have  been  careful 
to  speak  of  this  as  a  picture,  not  as  a  hypothesis.  It  is 
a  graphical  representation  of  the  things  we  are  talking 
about  which  supplies  us  with  insight  and  guidance. 
What  we  glean  from  the  picture  can  be  expressed  in  a 
more  non-committal  way  by  saying  that  space-time  has 
non-Euclidean  geometry.  The  terms  "curved  space" 
and  "non-Euclidean  space"  are  used  practically  synony- 
mously; but  they  suggest  rather  different  points  of  view. 
When  we  were  trying  to  conceive  finite  and  unbounded 
space  (p.  81)  the  difficult  step  was  the  getting  rid  of 
the  inside  and  the  outside  of  the  hypersphere.  There  is 
a  similar  step  in  the  transition  from  curved  space  to 
non-Euclidean  space — the  dropping  of  all  relations  to 
an  external  (and  imaginary)  scaffolding  and  the  holding 
on  to  those  relations  which  exist  within  the  space  itself. 
If  you  ask  what  is  the  distance  from  Glasgow  to  New 
York  there  are  two  possible  replies.  One  man  will  tell 
you  the  distance  measured  over  the  surface  of  the 
ocean;  another  will  recollect  that  there  is  a  still  shorter 
distance  by  tunnel  through  the  earth.  The  second  man 
makes  use  of  a  dimension  which  the  first  had  put  out 
of  mind.  But  if  two  men  do  not  agree  as  to  distances, 
they  will  not  agree  as  to  geometry;  for  geometry  treats 
of  the  laws  of  distances.  To  forget  or  to  be  ignorant  of 
a  dimension  lands  us  into  a  different  geometry.  Dis- 
tances for  the  second  man  obey  a  Euclidean  geometry 
of  three  dimensions;  distances   for  the   first  man   obey 


158         GRAVITATION— THE  EXPLANATION 

a  non-Euclidean  geometry  of  two  dimensions.  And  so 
if  you  concentrate  your  attention  on  the  earth's  surface 
so  hard  that  you  forget  that  there  is  an  inside  or  an 
outside  to  it,  you  will  say  that  it  is  a  two-dimensional 
manifold  with  non-Euclidean  geometry;  but  if  you 
recollect  that  there  is  three-dimensional  space  all  round 
which  affords  shorter  ways  of  getting  from  point  to 
point,  you  can  fly  back  to  Euclid  after  all.  You  will  then 
"explain  away"  the  non-Euclidean  geometry  by  saying 
that  what  you  at  first  took  for  distances  were  not  the 
proper  distances.  This  seems  to  be  the  easiest  way  of 
seeing  how  a  non-Euclidean  geometry  can  arise — 
through  mislaying  a  dimension — but  we  must  not  infer 
that  non-Euclidean  geometry  is  impossible  unless  it  arises 
from  this  cause. 

In  our  four-dimensional  world  pervaded  by  gravitation 
the  distances  obey  a  non-Euclidean  geometry.  Is  this 
because  we  are  concentrating  attention  wholly  on  its 
four  dimensions  and  have  missed  the  short  cuts  through 
regions  beyond?  By  the  aid  of  six  extra  dimensions  we 
can  return  to  Euclidean  geometry;  in  that  case  our  usual 
distances  from  point  to  point  in  the  world  are  not  the 
"true"  distances,  the  latter  taking  shorter  routes  through 
an  eighth  or  ninth  dimension.  To  bend  the  world  in  a 
super-world  of  ten  dimensions  so  as  to  provide  these 
short  cuts  does,  I  think,  help  us  to  form  an  idea 
of  the  properties  of  its  non-Euclidean  geometry;  at  any 
rate  the  picture  suggests  a  useful  vocabulary  for  de- 
scribing those  properties.  But  we  are  not  likely  to  accept 
these  extra  dimensions  as  a  literal  fact  unless  we  regard 
non-Euclidean  geometry  as  a  thing  which  at  all  costs 
must  be  explained  away. 

Of  the  two  alternatives — a  curved  manifold  in  a 
Euclidean  space  of  ten  dimensions  or  a  manifold  with 


NON-EUCLIDEAN  GEOMETRY  159 

non-Euclidean  geometry  and  no  extra  dimensions — 
which  is  right?  I  would  rather  not  attempt  a  direct 
answer,  because  I  fear  I  should  get  lost  in  a  fog  of 
metaphysics.  But  I  may  say  at  once  that  I  do  not  take 
the  ten  dimensions  seriously;  whereas  I  take  the  non- 
Euclidean  geometry  of  the  world  very  seriously,  and 
I  do  not  regard  it  as  a  thing  which  needs  explaining 
away.  The  view,  which  some  of  us  were  taught  at 
school,  that  the  truth  of  Euclid's  axioms  can  be  seen  in- 
tuitively, is  universally  rejected  nowadays.  We  can  no 
more  settle  the  laws  of  space  by  intuition  than  we  can 
settle  the  laws  of  heredity.  If  intuition  is  ruled  out,  the 
appeal  must  be  to  experiment — genuine  open-minded  ex- 
periment unfettered  by  any  preconception  as  to  what  the 
verdict  ought  to  be.  We  must  not  afterwards  go  back 
on  the  experiments  because  they  make  out  space  to  be 
very  slightly  non-Euclidean.  It  is  quite  true  that  a  way 
out  could  be  found.  By  inventing  extra  dimensions  we 
can  make  the  non-Euclidean  geometry  of  the  world 
depend  on  a  Euclidean  geometry  of  ten  dimensions;  had 
the  world  proved  to  be  Euclidean  we  could,  I  believe, 
have  made  its  geometry  depend  on  a  non-Euclidean 
geometry  of  ten  dimensions.  No  one  would  treat  the 
latter  suggestion  seriously,  and  no  reason  can  be  given 
for  treating  the  former  more  seriously. 

I  do  not  think  that  the  six  extra  dimensions  have  any 
stalwart  defenders;  but  we.  often  meet  with  attempts  to 
reimpose  Euclidean  geometry  on  the  world  in  another 
way.  The  proposal,  which  is  made  quite  unblushingly, 
is  that  since  our  measured  lengths  do  not  obey  Euclidean 
geometry  we  must  apply  corrections  to  them — cook  them 
— till  they  do.  A  closely  related  view  often  advocated 
is  that  space  is  neither  Euclidean  nor  non-Euclidean; 
it  is   all   a   matter   of  convention   and   we   are   free   to 


i6o         GRAVITATION— THE  EXPLANATION 

adopt  any  geometry  we  choose.*  Naturally  if  we  hold 
ourselves  free  to  apply  any  correction  we  like  to  our 
experimental  measures  we  can  make  them  obey  any 
law;  but  was  it  worth  while  saying  this?  The  asser- 
tion that  any  kind  of  geometry  is  permissible  could  only 
be  made  on  the  assumption  that  lengths  have  no  fixed 
value — that  the  physicist  does  not  (or  ought  not  to) 
mean  anything  in  particular  when  he  talks  of  length. 
I  am  afraid  I  shall  have  a  difficulty  in  making  my 
meaning  clear  to  those  who  start  from  the  assumption 
that  my  words  mean  nothing  in  particular;  but  for  those 
who  will  accord  them  some  meaning  I  will  try  to  remove 
any  possible  doubt.  The  physicist  is  accustomed  to  state 
lengths  to  a  great  number  of  significant  figures;  to 
ascertain  the  significance  of  these  lengths  we  must  notice 
how  they  are  derived;  and  we  find  that  they  are  derived 
from  a  comparison  with  the  extension  of  a  standard  of 
specified  material  constitution.  (We  may  pause  to  notice 
that  the  extension  of  a  standard  material  configuration 
may  rightly  be  regarded  as  one  of  the  earliest  subjects 
of  inquiry  in  a  physical  survey  of  our  environment.) 
These  lengths  are  a  gateway  through  which  knowledge 
of  the  world  around  us  is  sought.  Whether  or  not  they 
will  remain  prominent  in  the  final  picture  of  world- 
structure  will  transpire  as  the  research  proceeds;  we  do 
not  prejudge  that.  Actually  we  soon  find  that  space- 
lengths  or  time-lengths  taken  singly  are  relative,  and  only 

*  As  a  recent  illustration  of  this  attitude  I  may  refer  to  Bertrand 
Russell's  Analysis  of  Matter,  p.  78 — a  book  with  which  I  do  not  often 
seriously  disagree.  "Whereas  Eddington  seems  to  regard  it  as  necessary 
to  adopt  Einstein's  variable  space,  Whitehead  regards  it  as  necessary 
to  reject  it.  For  my  part,  I  do  not  see  why  we  should  agree  with  either 
view;  the  matter  seems  to  be  one  of  convenience  in  the  interpretation  of 
formulae."  Russell's  view  is  commended  in  a  review  by  C.  D.  Broad. 
See  also  footnote,  p.  142. 


NON-EUCLIDEAN  GEOMETRY  161 

a  combination  of  them  could  be  expected  to  appear 
even  in  the  humblest  capacity  in  the  ultimate  world- 
structure.  Meanwhile  the  first  step  through  the  gate- 
way takes  us  to  the  geometry  obeyed  by  these  lengths 
— very  nearly  Euclidean,  but  actually  non-Euclidean  and, 
as  we  have  seen,  a  distinctive  type  of  non-Euclidean 
geometry  in  which  the  ten  principal  coefficients  of  cur- 
vature vanish.  We  have  shown  in  this  chapter  that 
the  limitation  is  not  arbitrary;  it  is  a  necessary  property 
of  lengths  expressed  in  terms  of  the  extension  of  a  ma- 
terial standard,  though  it  might  have  been  surprising  if 
it  had  occurred  in  lengths  defined  otherwise.  Must  we 
stop  to  notice  the  interjection  that  if  we  had  meant 
something  different  by  length  we  should  have  found  a 
different  geometry?  Certainly  we  should;  and  if  we 
had  meant  something  different  by  electric  force  we  should 
have  found  equations  different  from  Maxwell's  equations. 
Not  only  empirically  but  also  by  theoretical  reasoning, 
we  reach  the  geometry  which  we  do  because  our  lengths 
mean  what  they  do. 

I  have  too  long  delayed  dealing  with  the  criticism  of 
the  pure  mathematician  who  is  under  the  impression 
that  geometry  is  a  subject  that  belongs  entirely  to  him. 
Each  branch  of  experimental  knowledge  tends  to  have 
associated  with  it  a  specialised  body  of  mathematical 
investigations.  The  pure  mathematician,  at  first  called  in 
as  servant,  presently  likes  to  assert  himself  as  master; 
the  connexus  of  mathematical  propositions  becomes  for 
him  the  main  subject,  and  he  does  not  ask  permission 
from  Nature  when  he  wishes  to  vary  or  generalise  the 
original  premises.  Thus  he  can  arrive  at  a  geometry 
unhampered  by  any  restriction  from  actual  space  meas- 
ures; a  potential  theory  unhampered  by  any  question 
as  to  how  gravitational  and  electrical  potentials  really 


1 62         GRAVITATION— THE  EXPLANATION 

behave;  a  hydrodynamics  of  perfect  fluids  doing  things 
which  it  would  be  contrary  to  the  nature  of  any  material 
fluid  to  do.  But  it  seems  to  be  only  in  geometry  that 
he  has  forgotten  that  there  ever  was  a  physical  subject 
of  the  same  name,  and  even  resents  the  application  of 
the  name  to  anything  but  his  network  of  abstract  math- 
ematics. I  do  not  think  it  can  be  disputed  that,  both 
etymologically  and  traditionally,  geometry  is  the  science 
of  measurement  of  the  space  around  us;  and  however 
much  the  mathematical  superstructure  may  now  over- 
weigh  the  observational  basis,  it  is  properly  speaking  an 
experimental  science.  This  is  fully  recognised  in  the 
"reformed"  teaching  of  geometry  in  schools;  boys  are 
taught  to  verify  by  measurement  that  certain  of  the 
geometrical  propositions  are  true  or  nearly  true.  No 
one  questions  the  advantage  of  an  unfettered  develop- 
ment of  geometry  as  a  pure  mathematical  subject;  but 
only  in  so  far  as  this  subject  is  linked  to  the  quantities 
arising  out  of  observation  and  measurement,  will  it  find 
mention  in  a  discussion  of  the  Nature  of  the  Physical 
World. 


Chapter  VIII 

MAN'S  PLACE  IN  THE  UNIVERSE 

The  Sidereal  Universe.  The  largest  telescopes  reveal 
about  a  thousand  million  stars.  Each  increase  in  tele- 
scopic power  adds  to  the  number  and  we  can  scarcely 
set  a  limit  to  the  multitude  that  must  exist.  Nevertheless 
there  are  signs  of  exhaustion,  and  it  is  clear  that  the 
distribution  which  surrounds  us  does  not  extend  uni- 
formly through  infinite  space.  At  first  an  increase  in 
light-grasp  by  one  magnitude  brings  into  view  three 
times  as  many  stars;  but  the  factor  diminishes  so  that 
at  the  limit  of  faintness  reached  by  the  giant  telescopes 
a  gain  of  one  magnitude  multiplies  the  number  of  stars 
seen  by  only  1.8,  and  the  ratio  at  that  stage  is  rapidly 
decreasing.  It  is  as  though  we  are  approaching  a  limit 
at  which  increase  of  power  will  not  bring  into  view  very 
many  additional  stars. 

Attempts  have  been  made  to  find  the  whole  number 
of  stars  by  a  risky  extrapolation  of  these  counts,  and 
totals  ranging  from  3000  to  30,000  millions  are  some- 
times quoted.  But  the  difficulty  is  that  the  part  of  the 
stellar  universe  which  we  mainly  survey  is  a  local  con- 
densation or  star-cloud  forming  part  of  a  much  greater 
system.  In  certain  directions  in  the  sky  our  telescopes 
penetrate  to  the  limits  of  the  system,  but  in  other  direc- 
tions the  extent  is  too  great  for  us  to  fathom.  The 
Milky  Way,  which  on  a  dark  night  forms  a  gleaming 
belt  round  the  sky,  shows  the  direction  in  which  there 
lie  stars  behind  stars  until  vision  fails.  This  great 
flattened  distribution  is  called  the  Galactic  System.  It 
forms  a  disc  of  thickness  small  compared  to  its  areal 

163 


164  MAN'S  PLACE  IN  THE  UNIVERSE 

extent.  It  is  partly  broken  up  into  subordinate  con- 
densations, which  are  probably  coiled  in  spiral  form  like 
the  spiral  nebulae  which  are  observed  in  great  numbers 
in  the  heavens.  The  centre  of  the  galactic  system  lies 
somewhere  in  the  direction  of  the  constellation  Sagit- 
tarius; it  is  hidden  from  us  not  only  by  great  distance  but 
also  to  some  extent  by  tracts  of  obscuring  matter  (dark 
nebulosity)  which  cuts  off  the  light  of  the  stars  behind. 

We  must  distinguish  then  between  our  local  star- 
cloud  and  the  great  galactic  system  of  which  it  is  a  part. 
Mainly  (but  not  exclusively)  the  star-counts  relate  to 
the  local  star-cloud,  and  it  is  this  which  the  largest 
telescopes  are  beginning  to  exhaust.  It  too  has  a  flat- 
tened form — flattened  nearly  in  the  same  plane  as  the 
galactic  system.  If  the  galactic  system  is  compared  to 
a  disc,  the  local  star-cloud  may  be  compared  to  a  bun, 
its  thickness  being  about  one-third  of  its  lateral  ex- 
tension. Its  size  is  such  that  light  takes  at  least  2000 
years  to  cross  from  one  side  to  the  other;  this  measure- 
ment is  necessarily  rough  because  it  relates  to  a  vague 
condensation  which  is  probably  not  sharply  separated 
from  other  contiguous  condensations.  The  extent  of 
the  whole  spiral  is  of  the  order  100,000  light  years.  It 
can  scarcely  be  doubted  that  the  flattened  form  of  the 
system  is  due  to  rapid  rotation,  and  indeed  there  is 
direct  evidence  of  strong  rotational  velocity;  but  it  is 
one  of  the  unexplained  mysteries  of  evolution  that 
nearly  all  celestial  bodies  have  come  to  be  endowed  with 
fast  rotation. 

Amid  this  great  population  the  sun  is  a  humble  unit. 
It  is  a  very  ordinary  star  about  midway  in  the  scale  of 
brilliancy.  We  know  of  stars  which  give  at  least  10,000 
times  the  light  of  the  sun;  we  know  also  of  stars  which 
give  1/10,000  of  its  light.     But  those  of  inferior  light 


THE  SIDEREAL  UNIVERSE  165 

greatly  outnumber  those  of  superior  light.  In  mass,  in 
surface  temperature,  in  bulk,  the  sun  belongs  to  a  very 
common  class  of  stars;  its  speed  of  motion  is  near  the 
average;  it  shows  none  of  the  more  conspicuous  phe- 
nomena such  as  variability  which  excite  the  attention 
of  astronomers.  In  the  community  of  stars  the  sun 
corresponds  to  a  respectable  middle-class  citizen.  It 
happens  to  be  quite  near  the  centre  of  the  local  star- 
cloud;  but  this  apparently  favoured  position  is  dis- 
counted by  the  fact  that  the  star-cloud  itself  is  placed 
very  eccentrically  in  relation  to  the  galactic  system,  being 
in  fact  near  the  confines  of  it.  We  cannot  claim  to  be 
at  the  hub  of  the  universe. 

The  contemplation  of  the  galaxy  impresses  us  with 
the  insignificance  of  our  own  little  world;  but  we  have 
to  go  still  lower  in  the  valley  of  humiliation.  The 
galactic  system  is  one  among  a  million  or  more  spiral 
nebulae.  There  seems  now  to  be  no  doubt  that,  as  has 
long  been  suspected,  the  spiral  nebulae  are  "island  uni- 
verses" detached  from  our  own.  They  too  are  great 
systems  of  stars — or  systems  in  the  process  of  developing 
into  stars — built  on  the  same  disc-like  plan.  We  see 
some  of  them  edgeways  and  can  appreciate  the  flatness 
of  the  disc;  others  are  broadside  on  and  show  the  ar- 
rangement of  the  condensations  in  the  form  of  a  double 
spiral.  Many  show  the  effects  of  dark  nebulosity 
breaking  into  the  regularity -and  blotting  out  the  star- 
light. In  a  few  of  the  nearest  spirals  it  is  possible  to 
detect  the  brightest  of  the  stars  individually;  variable 
stars  and  novae  (or  "new  stars")  are  observed  as  in  our 
own  system.  From  the  apparent  magnitudes  of  the  stars 
of  recognisable  character  (especially  the  Cepheid  vari- 
ables) it  is  possible  to  judge  the  distance.  The  nearest 
spiral  nebula  is  850,000  light  years  away. 


166  MAN'S  PLACE  IN  THE  UNIVERSE 

From  the  small  amount  of  data  yet  collected  it  would 
seem  that  our  own  nebula  or  galactic  system  is  ex- 
ceptionally large;  it  is  even  suggested  that  if  the  spiral 
nebulae  are  "islands"  the  galactic  system  is  a  "con- 
tinent". But  we  can  scarcely  venture  to  claim  premier 
rank  without  much  stronger  evidence.  At  all  events 
these  other  universes  are  aggregations  of  the  order  of 
ioo  million  stars. 

Again  the  question  raises  itself,  How  far  does  this 
distribution  extend?  Not  the  stars  this  time  but  uni- 
verses stretch  one  behind  the  other  beyond  sight.  Does 
this  distribution  too  come  to  an  end?  It  may  be  that 
imagination  must  take  another  leap,  envisaging  super- 
systems  which  surpass  the  spiral  nebulae  as  the  spiral 
nebulae  surpass  the  stars.  But  there  is  one  feeble  gleam 
of  evidence  that  perhaps  this  time  the  summit  of  the 
hierarchy  has  been  reached,  and  that  the  system  of 
the  spirals  is  actually  the  whole  world.  As  has  already 
been  explained  the  modern  view  is  that  space  is  finite — 
finite  though  unbounded.  In  such  a  space  light  which 
has  travelled  an  appreciable  part  of  the  way  "round  the 
world"  is  slowed  down  in  its  vibrations,  with  the  result 
that  all  spectral  lines  are  displaced  towards  the  red. 
Ordinarily  we  interpret  such  a  red  displacement  as  sig- 
nifying receding  velocity  in  the  line  of  sight.  Now  it  is 
a  striking  fact  that  a  great  majority  of  the  spirals  which 
have  been  measured  show  large  receding  velocities  often 
exceeding  iooo  kilometres  per  second.  There  are  only 
two  serious  exceptions,  and  these  are  the  largest  spirals 
which  must  be  nearer  to  us  than  most  of  the  others. 
On  ordinary  grounds  it  would  be  difficult  to  explain  why 
these  other  universes  should  hurry  away  from  us  so  fast 
and  so  unanimously.  Why  should  they  shun  us  like 
a  plague?     But  the  phenomenon  is  intelligible  if  what 


THE  SCALE  OF  TIME  167 

has  really  been  observed  is  the  slowing  down  of  vibra- 
tions consequent  on  the  light  from  these  objects  having 
travelled  an  appreciable  part  of  the  way  round  the  world. 
On  that  theory  the  radius  of  space  is  of  the  order  twenty 
times  the  average  distance  of  the  nebulae  observed,  or 
say  100  million  light  years.  That  leaves  room  for  a 
few  million  spirals;  but  there  is  nothing  beyond.  There 
is  no  beyond — in  spherical  space  "beyond"  brings  us 
back  towards  the  earth  from  the  opposite  direction.* 

The  Scale  of  Time.  The  corridor  of  time  stretches  back 
through  the  past.  We  can  have  no  conception  how  it 
all  began.  But  at  some  stage  we  imagine  the  void  to 
have  been  filled  with  matter  rarified  beyond  the  most 
tenuous  nebula.  The  atoms  sparsely  strewn  move  hither 
and  thither  in  formless  disorder. 

Behold  the  throne 
Of  Chaos  and  his  dark  pavilion  spread 
Wide  on  the  wasteful  deep. 

Then  slowly  the  power  of  gravitation  is  felt.  Centres 
of  condensation  begin  to  establish  themselves  and  draw 
in  other  matter.  The  first  partitions  are  the  star-systems 
such  as  our  galactic  system;  sub-condensations  separate 
the  star-clouds  or  clusters;  these  divide  again  to  give 
the  stars. 

Evolution  has  not  reached  the  same  development  in 

*A  very  much  larger  radius  of  space  (io11  light  years)  has  recently 
been  proposed  by  Hubble;  but  the  basis  of  his  calculation,  though  con- 
cerned with  spiral  nebulae,  is  different  and  to  my  mind  unacceptable. 
It  rests  on  an  earlier  theory  of  closed  space  proposed  by  Einstein  which 
has  generally  been  regarded  as  superseded.  The  theory  given  above  (due 
to  W.  de  Sitter)  is,  of  course,  very  speculative,  but  it  is  the  only  clue  we 
possess  as  to  the  dimensions  of  space. 


168  MAN'S  PLACE  IN  THE  UNIVERSE 

all  parts.  We  observe  nebulae  and  clusters  in  different 
stages  of  advance.  Some  stars  are  still  highly  diffuse; 
others  are  concentrated  like  the  sun  with  density  greater 
than  water;  others,  still  more  advanced,  have  shrunk  to 
unimaginable  density.  But  no  doubt  can  be  entertained 
that  the  genesis  of  the  stars  is  a  single  process  of  evolu- 
tion which  has  passed  and  is  passing  over  a  primordial 
distribution.  Formerly  it  was  freely  speculated  that  the 
birth  of  a  star  was  an  individual  event  like  the  birth  of 
an  animal.  From  time  to  time  two  long  extinct  stars 
would  collide  and  be  turned  into  vapour  by  the  energy  of 
the  collision;  condensation  would  follow  and  life  as  a 
luminous  body  would  begin  all  over  again.  We  can 
scarcely  affirm  that  this  will  never  occur  and  that  the 
sun  is  not  destined  to  have  a  second  or  third  innings; 
but  it  is  clear  from  the  various  relations  traced  among 
the  stars  that  the  present  stage  of  existence  of  the 
sidereal  universe  is  the  first  innings.  Groups  of  stars  are 
found  which  move  across  the  sky  with  common  proper 
motion;  these  must  have  had  a  single  origin  and  cannot 
have  been  formed  by  casual  collisions.  Another  aban- 
doned speculation  is  that  lucid  stars  may  be  the  excep- 
tion, and  that  there  may  exist  thousands  of  dead  stars 
for  every  one  that  is  seen  shining.  There  are  ways  of 
estimating  the  total  mass  in  interstellar  space  by  its 
gravitational  effect  on  the  average  speed  of  the  stars; 
it  is  found  that  the  lucid  stars  account  for  something 
approaching  the  total  mass  admissible  and  the  amount 
left  over  for  dark  stars  is  very  limited. 

Biologists  and  geologists  carry  back  the  history  of  the 
earth  some  thousand  million  years.  Physical  evidence 
based  on  the  rate  of  transmutation  of  radioactive  sub- 
stances seems  to  leave  no  escape  from  the  conclusion 
that  the  older  (Archaean)  rocks  in  the  earth's  crust  were 


PLURALITY  OF  WORLDS  169 

laid  down  1200  million  years  ago.  The  sun  must  have 
been  burning  still  longer,  living  (we  now  think)  on  its 
own  matter  which  dissolves  bit  by  bit  into  radiation. 
According  to  the  theoretical  time-scale,  which  seems 
best  supported  by  astronomical  evidence,  the  beginning 
of  the  sun  as  a  luminous  star  must  be  dated  five  billion 
(5-I012)  years  ago.  The  theory  which  assigns  this  date 
cannot  be  trusted  confidently,  but  it  seems  a  reasonably 
safe  conclusion  that  the  sun's  age  does  not  exceed  this 
limit.  The  future  is  not  so  restricted  and  the  sun  may 
continue  as  a  star  of  increasing  feebleness  for  50  or 
500  billion  years.  The  theory  of  sub-atomic  energy 
has  prolonged  the  life  of  a  star  from  millions  to  bil- 
lions of  years,  and  we  may  speculate  on  processes 
of  rejuvenescence  which  might  prolong  the  exist- 
ence of  the  sidereal  universe  from  billions  to  trillions 
of  years.  But  unless  we  can  circumvent  the  second 
law  of  thermodynamics — which  is  as  much  as  to 
say  unless  we  can  find  cause  for  time  to  run  back- 
wards— the  ultimate  decay  draws  surely  nearer  and  the 
world  will  at  the  last  come  to  a  state  of  uniform 
changelessness. 

Does  this  prodigality  of  matter,  of  space,   of  time, 
find  its  culmination  in  Man? 

Plurality  of  Worlds.  I  will  here  put  together  the  present 
astronomical  evidence  as  tQ  the  habitability  of  other 
worlds.  The  popular  idea  that  an  answer  to  this  ques- 
tion is  one  of  the  main  aims  of  the  study  of  celestial 
objects  is  rather  disconcerting  to  the  astronomer.  Any- 
thing that  he  has  to  contribute  is  of  the  nature  of  frag- 
mentary hints  picked  up  in  the  course  of  investigations 
with  more  practicable  and  commonplace  purposes. 
Nevertheless,  the  mind  is  irresistibly  drawn  to  play  with 


170  MAN'S  PLACE  IN  THE  UNIVERSE 

the  thought  that  somewhere  in  the  universe  there  may 
be  other  beings  "a  little  lower  than  the  angels"  whom 
Man  may  regard  as  his  equals — or  perhaps  his 
superiors. 

It  is  idle  to  guess  the  forms  that  life  might  take  in  con- 
ditions differing  from  those  of  our  planet.  If  I  have 
rightly  understood  the  view  of  palaeontologists,  mam- 
malian life  is  the  third  terrestrial  dynasty — Nature's 
third  attempt  to  evolve  an  order  of  life  sufficiently  flex- 
ible to  changing  conditions  and  fitted  to  dominate  the 
earth.  Minor  details  in  the  balance  of  circumstances 
must  greatly  affect  the  possibility  of  life  and  the  type  of 
organism  destined  to  prevail.  Some  critical  branch- 
point in  the  course  of  evolution  must  be  negotiated  be- 
fore life  can  rise  to  the  level  of  consciousness.  All  this 
is  remote  from  the  astronomer's  line  of  study.  To  avoid 
endless  conjecture  I  shall  assume  that  the  required  con- 
ditions of  habitability  are  not  unlike  those  on  the  earth, 
and  that  if  such  conditions  obtain  life  will  automatically 
make  its  appearance. 

We  survey  first  the  planets  of  the  solar  system;  of 
these  only  Venus  and  Mars  seem  at  all  eligible.  Venus, 
so  far  as  we  know,  would  be  well  adapted  for  life 
similar  to  ours.  It  is  about  the  same  size  as  the  earth, 
nearer  the  sun  but  probably  not  warmer,  and  it  possesses 
an  atmosphere  of  satisfactory  density.  Spectroscopic  ob- 
servation has  unexpectedly  failed  to  give  any  indication  of 
oxygen  in  the  upper  atmosphere  and  thus  suggests  a 
doubt  as  to  whether  free  oxygen  exists  on  the  planet; 
but  at  present  we  hesitate  to  draw  so  definite  an  infer- 
ence. If  transplanted  to  Venus  we  might  perhaps  con- 
tinue to  live  without  much  derangement  of  habit — 
except  that  I  personally  would  have  to  find  a  new  pro- 
fession, since  Venus  is  not  a  good  place  for  astronomers. 


PLURALITY  OF  WORLDS  171 

It  is  completely  covered  with  cloud  or  mist.  For  this 
reason  no  definite  surface  markings  can  be  made  out, 
and  it  is  still  uncertain  how  fast  it  rotates  on  its  axis 
and  in  which  direction  the  axis  lies.  One  curious  theory 
may  be  mentioned  though  it  should  perhaps  not  be  taken 
too  seriously.  It  is  thought  by  some  that  the  great 
cavity  occupied  by  the  Pacific  Ocean  is  a  scar  left  by  the 
moon  when  it  was  first  disrupted  from  the  earth.  Evi- 
dently this  cavity  fulfils  an  important  function  in  drain- 
ing away  superfluous  water,  and  if  it  were  filled  up 
practically  all  the  continental  area  would  be  submerged. 
Thus  indirectly  the  existence  of  dry  land  is  bound  up 
with  the  existence  of  the  moon.  But  Venus  has  no  moon, 
and  since  it  seems  to  be  similar  to  the  earth  in  other 
respects,  it  may  perhaps  be  inferred  that  it  is  a  world 
which  is  all  ocean — where  fishes  are  supreme.  The 
suggestion  at  any  rate  serves  to  remind  us  that  the 
destinies  of  organic  life  may  be  determined  by  what 
are  at  first  sight  irrelevant  accidents. 

The  sun  is  an  ordinary  star  and  the  earth  is  an 
ordinary  planet,  but  the  moon  is  not  an  ordinary  satel- 
lite. No  other  known  satellite  is  anything  like  so  large 
in  proportion  to  the  planet  which  it  attends.  The  moon 
contains  about  1/80  part  of  the  mass  of  the  earth  which 
seems  a  small  ratio;  but  it  is  abnormally  great  compared 
with  other  satellites.  The  next  highest  ratio  is  found 
in  the  system  of  Saturn  whose  largest  satellite  Titan  has 
1/4000  of  the  planet's  mass.  Very  special  circum- 
stances must  have  occurred  in  the  history  of  the  earth 
to  have  led  to  the  breaking  away  of  so  unusual  a  frac- 
tion of  the  mass.  The  explanation  proposed  by  Sir 
George  Darwin,  which  is  still  regarded  as  most  prob- 
able, is  that  a  resonance  in  period  occurred  between 
the  solar  tides  and  the  natural  free  period  of  vibration 


172  MAN'S  PLACE  IN  THE  UNIVERSE 

of  the  globe  of  the  earth.  The  tidal  deformation  of  the 
earth  thus  grew  to  large  amplitude,  ending  in  a  cata- 
clysm which  separated  the  great  lump  of  material  that 
formed  the  moon.  Other  planets  escaped  this  dangerous 
coincidence  of  period,  and  their  satellites  separated  by- 
more  normal  development.  If  ever  I  meet  a  being  who 
has  lived  in  another  world,  I  shall  feel  very  humble  in 
most  respects,  but  I  expect  to  be  able  to  boast  a  little 
about  the  moon. 

Mars  is  the  only  planet  whose  solid  surface  can  be 
seen  and  studied;  and  it  tempts  us  to  consider  the  possi- 
bility of  life  in  more  detail.  Its  smaller  size  leads  to 
considerably  different  conditions;  but  the  two  essentials, 
air  and  water,  are  both  present  though  scanty.  The 
Martian  atmosphere  is  thinner  than  our  own  but  it  is 
perhaps  adequate.  It  has  been  proved  to  contain  oxy- 
gen. There  is  no  ocean;  the  surface  markings  repre- 
sent, not  sea  and  land,  but  red  desert  and  darker  ground 
which  is  perhaps  moist  and  fertile.  A  conspicuous  fea- 
ture is  the  white  cap  covering  the  pole  which  is  clearly 
a  deposit  of  snow;  it  must  be  quite  shallow  since  it  melts 
away  completely  in  the  summer.  Photographs  show 
from  time  to  time  indubitable  clouds  which  blot  out 
temporarily  large  areas  of  surface  detail;  clear  weather, 
however,  is  more  usual.  The  air,  if  cloudless,  is  slightly 
hazy.  W.  H.  Wright  has  shown  this  very  convincingly 
by  comparing  photographs  taken  with  light  of  dif- 
ferent wave-lengths.  Light  of  short  wave-length  is 
much  scattered  by  haze  and  accordingly  the  ordinary 
photographs  are  disappointingly  blurry.  Much  sharper 
surface-detail  is  shown  when  visual  yellow  light  is 
employed  (a  yellow  screen  being  commonly  used  to 
adapt  visual  telescopes  for  photography)  ;  being  of 
longer  wave-length   the  visual  rays  penetrate   the   haze 


PLURALITY  OF  WORLDS  173 

more  easily.*     Still  clearer  detail  is  obtained  by  photo- 
graphing with  the  long  infra-red  waves. 

Great  attention  has  lately  been  paid  to  the  deter- 
mination of  the  temperature  of  the  surface  of  Mars;  it 
is  possible  to  find  this  by  direct  measurement  of  the  heat 
rediated  to  us  from  different  parts  of  the  surface.  The 
results,  though  in  many  respects  informative,  are 
scarcely  accurate  and  accordant  enough  to  give  a  defi- 
nite idea  of  the  climatology.  Naturally  the  tempera- 
ture varies  a  great  deal  between  day  and  night  and  in 
different  latitudes;  but  on  the  average  the  conditions 
are  decidedly  chilly.  Even  at  the  equator  the  tempera- 
ture falls  below  freezing  point  at  sunset.  If  we  accepted 
the  present  determinations  as  definitive  we  should  have 
some  doubt  as  to  whether  life  could  endure  the  con- 
ditions. 

In  one  of  Huxley's  Essays  there  occurs  the  passage 
"Until  human  life  is  longer  and  the  duties  of  the 
present  press  less  heavily  I  do  not  think  that  wise  men 
will  occupy  themselves  with  Jovian  or  Martian  natural 
history."  To-day  it  would  seem  that  Martian  natural 
history  is  not  altogether  beyond  the  limits  of  serious 
science.  At  least  the  surface  of  Mars  shows  a  seasonal 
change  such  as  we  might  well  imagine  the  forest-clad 
earth  would  show  to  an  outside  onlooker.  This  seasonal 
change  of  appearance  is  very  conspicuous  to  the  atten- 
tive observer.  As  the  spring  in  one  hemisphere  advances 
(I  mean,  of  course,  the  Martian  spring),  the  darker 
areas,  which  are  at  first  few  and  faint,  extend  and 
deepen  in  contrast.     The  same  regions  darken  year  after 

*  It  seems  to  have  been  a  fortunate  circumstance  that  the  pioneers 
of  Martian  photography  had  no  suitable  photographic  telescopes  and 
had  to  adapt  visual  telescopes — thus  employing  visual  (yellow)  light 
which,  as  it  turned  out,  was  essential  for  good  results. 


i74  MAN'S  PLACE  IN  THE  UNIVERSE 

year  at  nearly  the  same  date  in  the  Martian  calendar. 
It  may  be  that  there  is  an  inorganic  explanation;  the 
spring  rains  moisten  the  surface  and  change  its  colour. 
But  it  is  perhaps  unlikely  that  there  is  enough  rain 
to  bring  about  this  change  as  a  direct  effect.  It  is 
easier  to  believe  that  we  are  witnessing  the  annual 
awakening  of  vegetation  so  familiar  on  our  own 
planet. 

The  existence  of  oxygen  in  the  Martian  atmosphere 
supplies  another  argument  in  support  of  the  existence 
of  vegetable  life.  Oxygen  combines  freely  with  many 
elements,  and  the  rocks  in  the  earth's  crust  are  thirsty 
for  oxygen.  They  would  in  course  of  time  bring  about 
its  complete  disappearance  from  the  air,  were  it  not  that 
the  vegetation  extracts  it  from  the  soil  and  sets  it  free 
again.  If  oxygen  in  the  terrestrial  atmosphere  is  main- 
tained in  this  way,  it  would  seem  reasonable  to  assume 
that  vegetable  life  is  required  to  play  the  same  part  on 
Mars.  Taking  this  in  conjunction  with  the  evidence  of 
the  seasonal  changes  of  appearance,  a  rather  strong  case 
for  the  existence  of  vegetation  seems  to  have  been  made 
out. 

If  vegetable  life  must  be  admitted,  can  we  exclude 
animal  life?  I  have  come  to  the  end  of  the  astronomical 
data  and  can  take  no  responsibility  for  anything  further 
that  you  may  infer.  It  is  true  that  the  late  Prof.  Lowell 
argued  that  certain  more  or  less  straight  markings  on 
the  planet  represent  an  artificial  irrigation  system  and 
are  the  signs  of  an  advanced  civilisation;  but  this  theory 
has  not,  I  think,  won  much  support.  In  justice  to  the 
author  of  this  speculation  it  should  be  said  that  his  own 
work  and  that  of  his  observatory  have  made  a  magni- 
ficent contribution  to  our  knowledge  of  Mars;  but  few 
would  follow  him  all  the  way  on  the  more  picturesque 


FORMATION  OF  PLANETARY  SYSTEMS       175 

side  of  his  conclusions.*  Finally  we  may  stress  one 
point.  Mars  has  every  appearance  of  being  a  planet 
long  past  its  prime;  and  it  is  in  any  case  improbable  that 
two  planets  differing  so  much  as  Mars  and  the  Earth 
would  be  in  the  zenith  of  biological  development  con- 
temporaneously. 

Formation  of  Planetary  Systems.  If  the  planets  of  the 
solar  system  should  fail  us,  there  remain  some  thousands 
of  millions  of  stars  which  we  have  been  accustomed  to 
regard  as  suns  ruling  attendant  systems  of  planets.  It 
has  seemed  a  presumption,  bordering  almost  on  impiety, 
to  deny  to  them  life  of  the  same  order  of  creation  as 
ourselves.  It  would  indeed  be  rash  to  assume  that 
nowhere  else  in  the  universe  has  Nature  repeated  the 
strange  experiment  which  she  has  performed  on  the 
earth.  But  there  are  considerations  which  must  hold  us 
back  from  populating  the  universe  too  liberally. 

On  examining  the  stars  with  a  telescope  we  are  sur- 
prised to  find  how  many  of  those  which  appear  single 
points  to  the  eye  are  actually  two  stars  close  together. 
When  the  telescope  fails  to  separate  them  the  spectro- 
scope often  reveals  two  stars  in  orbital  revolution  round 
each  other.  At  least  one  star  in  three  is  double — a  pair 
of  self-luminous  globes  both  comparable  in  dimensions 
with  the  sun.  The  single  supreme  sun  is  accordingly 
not  the  only  product  of  evolution;  not  much  less  fre- 
quently the  development  has  taken  another  turn  and 
resulted  in  two  suns  closely  associated.  We  may  prob- 
ably rule  out  the  possibility  of  planets  in  double  stars. 

♦Mars  is  not  seen  under  favourable  conditions  except  from  low  lati- 
tudes and  high  altitudes.  Astronomers  who  have  not  these  advantages 
are  reluctant  to  form  a  decided  opinion  on  the  many  controversial  points 
that  have  arisen. 


176  MAN'S  PLACE  IN  THE  UNIVERSE 

Not  only  is  there  a  difficulty  in  ascribing  to  them  per- 
manent orbits  under  the  more  complicated  field  of  gravi- 
tation, but  a  cause  for  the  formation  of  planets  seems 
to  be  lacking.  The  star  has  satisfied  its  impulse  to 
fission  in  another  manner;  it  has  divided  into  two  nearly 
equal  portions  instead  of  throwing  off  a  succession  of 
tiny  fragments. 

The  most  obvious  cause  of  division  is  excessive  rota- 
tion. As  the  gaseous  globe  contracts  it  spins  fast  and 
faster  until  a  time  may  come  when  it  can  no  longer  hold 
together,  and  some  kind  of  relief  must  be  found.  Ac- 
cording to  the  nebular  hypothesis  of  Laplace  the  sun 
gained  relief  by  throwing  off  successively  rings  of  matter 
which  have  formed  the  planets.  But  were  it  not  for 
this  one  instance  of  a  planetary  system  which  is  known 
to  us,  we  should  have  concluded  from  the  thousands  of 
double  stars  in  the  sky  that  the  common  consequence  of 
excessive  rotation  is  to  divide  the  star  into  two  bodies 
of  equal  rank. 

It  might  still  be  held  that  the  ejection  of  a  planetary 
system  and  the  fission  into  a  double  star  are  alternative 
solutions  of  the  problem  arising  from  excessive  rotation, 
the  star  taking  one  course  or  the  other  according  to 
circumstances.  We  know  of  myriads  of  double  stars 
and  of  only  one  planetary  system;  but  in  any  case  it  is 
beyond  our  power  to  detect  other  planetary  systems  if 
they  exist.  We  can  only  appeal  to  the  results  of  theo- 
retical study  of  rotating  masses  of  gas;  the  work  pre- 
sents many  complications  and  the  results  may  not  be 
final;  but  the  researches  of  Sir  J.  H.  Jeans  lead  to  the 
conclusion  that  rotational  break-up  produces  a  double 
star  and  never  a  system  of  planets.  The  solar  system  is 
not  the  typical  product  of  development  of  a  star;  it  is 
not  even  a  common  variety  of  development;  it  is  a  freak. 


FORMATION  OF  PLANETARY  SYSTEMS       177 

By  elimination  of  alternatives  it  appears  that  a  con- 
figuration resembling  the  solar  system  would  only  be 
formed  if  at  a  certain  stage  of  condensation  an  unusual 
accident  had  occurred.  According  to  Jeans  the  accident 
was  the  close  approach  of  another  star  casually  pursuing 
its  way  through  space.  This  star  must  have  passed 
within  a  distance  not  far  outside  the  orbit  of  Neptune; 
it  must  not  have  passed  too  rapidly,  but  have  slowly 
overtaken  or  been  overtaken  by  the  sun.  By  tidal  dis- 
tortion it  raised  big  protuberances  on  the  sun,  and  caused 
it  to  spurt  out  filaments  of  matter  which  have  condensed 
to  form  the  planets.  That  was  more  than  a  thousand 
million  years  ago.  The  intruding  star  has  since  gone  on 
its  way  and  mingled  with  the  others;  its  legacy  of  a 
system  of  planets  remains,  including  a  globe  habitable 
by  man. 

Even  in  the  long  life  of  a  star  encounters  of  this  kind 
must  be  extremely  rare.  The  density  of  distribution  of 
stars  in  space  has  been  compared  to  that  of  twenty 
tennis-balls  roaming  the  whole  interior  of  the  earth. 
The  accident  that  gave  birth  to  the  solar  system  may  be 
compared  to  the  casual  approach  of  two  of  these  balls 
within  a  few  yards  of  one  another.  The  data  are  too 
vague  to  give  any  definite  estimate  of  the  odds  against 
this  occurence,  but  I  should  judge  that  perhaps  not  one 
in  a  hundred  millions  of  stars  can  have  undergone  this 
experience  in  the  right  stage  and  conditions  to  result  in 
the  formation  of  a  system  of  planets. 

However  doubtful  this  conclusion  as  to  the  rarity  of 
solar  systems  may  be,  it  is  a  useful  corrective  to  the  view 
too  facilely  adopted  which  looks  upon  every  star  as  a 
likely  minister  'to  life.  We  know  the  prodigality  of 
Nature.  How  many  acorns  are  scattered  for  one  that 
grows  to  an  oak?    And  need  she  be  more  careful  of  her 


i;8  MAN'S  PLACE  IN  THE  UNIVERSE 

stars  than  of  her  acorns?  If  indeed  she  has  no  grander 
aim  than  to  provide  a  home  for  her  greatest  experiment, 
Man,  it  would  be  just  like  her  methods  to  scatter  a  mil- 
lion stars  whereof  one  might  haply  achieve  her  purpose. 

The  number  of  possible  abodes  of  life  severely 
restricted  in  this  way  at  the  outset  may  no  doubt  be 
winnowed  down  further.  On  our  house-hunting  expedi- 
tion we  shall  find  it  necessary  to  reject  many  apparently 
eligible  mansions  on  points  of  detail.  Trivial  circum- 
stances may  decide  whether  organic  forms  originate  at 
all;  further  conditions  may  decide  whether  life  ascends 
to  a  complexity  like  ours  or  remains  in  a  lower  form. 
I  presume,  however,  that  at  the  end  of  the  weeding 
out  there  will  be  left  a  few  rival  earths  dotted  here  and 
there  about  the  universe. 

A  further  point  arises  if  we  have  especially  in  mind 
contemporaneous  life.  The  time  during  which  man  has 
been  on  the  earth  is  extremely  small  compared  with  the 
age  of  the  earth  or  of  the  sun.  There  is  no  obvious 
physical  reason  why,  having  once  arrived,  man  should 
not  continue  to  populate  the  earth  for  another  ten  billion 
years  or  so;  but — well,  can  you  contemplate  it?  Assum- 
ing that  the  stage  of  highly  developed  life  is  a  very 
small  fraction  of  the  inorganic  history  of  the  star,  the 
rival  earths  are  in  general  places  where  conscious  life 
has  already  vanished  or  is  yet  to  come.  I  do  not  think 
that  the  whole  purpose  of  the  Creation  has  been  staked 
on  the  one  planet  where  we  live;  and  in  the  long  run  we 
cannot  deem  ourselves  the  only  race  that  has  been  or 
will  be  gifted  with  the  mystery  of  consciousness.  But 
I  feel  inclined  to  claim  that  at  the  present  time  our  race 
is  supreme;  and  not  one  of  the  profusion  of  stars  in 
their  myriad  clusters  looks  down  on  scenes  comparable 
to  those  which  are  passing  beneath  the  rays  of  the  sun. 


Chapter  IX 
THE  QUANTUM  THEORY 

The  Origin  of  the  Trouble.  Nowadays  whenever  en- 
thusiasts meet  together  to  discuss  theoretical  physics  the 
talk  sooner  or  later  turns  in  a  certain  direction.  You 
leave  them  conversing  on  their  special  problems  or  the 
latest  discoveries;  but  return  after  an  hour  and  it  is  any 
odds  that  they  will  have  reached  an  all-engrossing  topic 
— the  desperate  state  of  their  ignorance.  This  is  not  a 
pose.  It  is  not  even  scientific  modesty,  because  the  atti- 
tude is  often  one  of  naive  surprise  that  Nature  should 
have  hidden  her  fundamental  secret  successfully  from 
such  powerful  intellects  as  ours.  It  is  simply  that  we 
have  turned  a  corner  in  the  path  of  progress  and  our 
ignorance  stands  revealed  before  us,  appalling  and  insist- 
ent. There  is  something  radically  wrong  with  the  pres- 
ent fundamental  conceptions  of  physics  and  we  do  not 
see  how  to  set  it  right. 

The  cause  of  all  this  trouble  is  a  little  thing  called  h 
which  crops  up  continually  in  a  wide  range  of  experi- 
ments. In  one  sense  we  know  just  what  h  is,  because 
there  are  a  variety  of  ways  of  measuring  it;  h  is 

.0000000000000000000000000065 5  erg-seconds. 

That  will  (rightly)  suggest  to  you  that  h  is  something 
very  small;  but  the  most  important  information  is  con- 
tained in  the  concluding  phrase  erg-seconds.  The  erg 
is  the  unit  of  energy  and  the  second  is  the  unit  of  time; 
so  that  we  learn  that  h  is  of  the  nature  of  energy  multi- 
plied by  time. 

Now  in  practical  life  it  does  not  often  occur  to  us  to 

179 


180  THE  QUANTUM  THEORY 

multiply  energy  by  time.  We  often  divide  energy  by 
time.  For  example,  the  motorist  divides  the  output  of 
energy  of  his  engine  by  time  and  so  obtains  the  horse- 
power. Conversely  an  electric  supply  company  multi- 
plies the  horse-power  or  kilowatts  by  the  number  of 
hours  of  consumption  and  sends  in  its  bill  accordingly. 
But  to  multiply  by  hours  again  would  seem  a  very  odd 
sort  of  thing  to  do. 

But  it  does  not  seem  quite  so  strange  when  we  look 
at  it  in  the  absolute  four-dimensional  world.  Quantities 
such  as  energy,  which  we  think  of  as  existing  at  an 
instant,  belong  to  three-dimensional  space,  and  they  need 
to  be  multiplied  by  a  duration  to  give  them  a  thickness 
before  they  can  be  put  into  the  four-dimensional  world. 
Consider  a  portion  of  space,  say  Great  Britain;  we 
should  describe  the  amount  of  humanity  in  it  as  40 
million  men.  But  consider  a  portion  of  space-time,  say 
Great  Britain  between  19 15  and  1925;  we  must  describe 
the  amount  of  humanity  in  it  as  400  million  man-years. 
To  describe  the  human  content  of  the  world  from  a 
space-time  point  of  view  we  have  to  take  a  unit  which  is 
limited  not  only  in  space  but  in  time.  Similarly  if  some 
other  kind  of  content  of  space  is  described  as  so  many 
ergs,  the  corresponding  content  of  a  region  of  space-time 
will  be  described  as  so  many  erg-seconds. 

We  call  this  quantity  in  the  four-dimensional  world 
which  is  the  analogue  or  adaptation  of  energy  in  the 
three-dimensional  world  by  the  technical  name  action.  The 
name  does  not  seem  to  have  any  special  appropriateness, 
but  we  have  to  accept  it.  Erg-seconds  or  action  belongs 
to  Minkowski's  world  which  is  common  to  all  observers, 
and  so  it  is  absolute.  It  is  one  of  the  very  few  absolute 
quantities  noticed  in  pre-relativity  physics.  Except  for 
action  and  entropy  (which  belongs  to  an  entirely  different 


THE  ORIGIN  OF  THE  TROUBLE  181 

class  of  physical  conceptions)  all  the  quantities  promi- 
nent in  pre-relativity  physics  refer  to  the  three-dimen- 
sional sections  which  are  different  for  different  observers. 

Long  before  the  theory  of  relativity  showed  us  that 
action  was  likely  to  have  a  special  importance  in  the 
scheme  of  Nature  on  account  of  its  absoluteness,  long 
before  the  particular  piece  of  action  h  began  to  turn  up 
in  experiments,  the  investigators  of  theoretical  dynamics 
were  making  great  use  of  action.  It  was  especially  the 
work  of  Sir  William  Hamilton  which  brought  it  to  the 
fore;  and  since  then  very  extensive  theoretical  develop- 
ments of  dynamics  have  been  made  on  this  basis.  I 
need  only  refer  to  the  standard  treatise  on  Analytical 
Dynamics  by  your  own  (Edinburgh)  Professor*,  which 
fairly  reeks  of  it.  It  was  not  difficult  to  appreciate  the 
fundamental  importance  and  significance  of  the  main 
principle;  but  it  must  be  confessed  that  to  the  non- 
specialist  the  interest  of  the  more  elaborate  develop- 
ments did  not  seem  very  obvious — except  as  an  ingenious 
way  of  making  easy  things  difficult.  In  the  end  the 
instinct  which  led  to  these  researches  has  justified  itself 
emphatically.  To  follow  any  of  the  progress  in  the 
quantum  theory  of  the  atom  since  about  19 17,  it  is 
necessary  to  have  plunged  rather  deeply  into  the  Hamil- 
tonian  theory  of  dynamics.  It  is  remarkable  that  just 
as  Einstein  found  ready  prepared  by  the  mathematicians 
the  Tensor  Calculus  which  he  needed  for  developing 
his  great  theory  of  gravitation,  so  the  quantum  physicists 
found  ready  for  them  an  extensive  action-theory  of 
dynamics  without  which  they  could  not  have  made  head- 
way. 

But  neither  the  absolute  importance  of  action  in  the 
four-dimensional   world,    nor   its    earlier   prominence    in 

*  Prof.  E.  T.  Whittaker. 


1 82  THE  QUANTUM  THEORY 

Hamiltonian  dynamics,  prepares  us  for  the  discovery 
that  a  particular  lump  of  it  can  have  a  special  import- 
ance. And  yet  a  lump  of  standard  size  6-55.  io~27  erg- 
seconds  is  continually  turning  up  experimentally.  It  is 
all  very  well  to  say  that  we  must  think  of  action  as 
atomic  and  regard  this  lump  as  the  atom  of  action.  We 
cannot  do  it.  We  have  been  trying  hard  for  the  last 
ten  years.  Our  present  picture  of  the  world  shows 
action  in  a  form  quite  incompatible  with  this  kind  of 
atomic  structure,  and  the  picture  will  have  to  be  redrawn. 
There  must  in  fact  be  a  radical  change  in  the  funda- 
mental conceptions  on  which  our  scheme  of  physics  is 
founded;  the  problem  is  to  discover  the  particular 
change  required.  Since  1925  new  ideas  have  been 
brought  into  the  subject  which  seem  to  make  the  dead- 
lock less  complete,  and  give  us  an  inkling  of  the  nature 
of  the  revolution  that  must  come;  but  there  has  been 
no  general  solution  of  the  difficulty.  The  new  ideas  will 
be  the  subject  of  the  next  chapter.  Here  it  seems  best 
to  limit  ourselves  to  the  standpoint  of  1925,  except  at 
the  very  end  of  the  chapter,  where  we  prepare  for  the 
transition. 

The  Atom  of  Action.  Remembering  that  action  has  two 
ingredients,  namely,  energy  and  time,  we  must  look  about 
in  Nature  for  a  definite  quantity  of  energy  with  which 
there  is  associated  some  definite  period  of  time.  That  is 
the  way  in  which  without  artificial  section  a  particular 
lump  of  action  can  be  separated  from  the  rest  of  the  action 
which  fills  the  universe.  For  example,  the  energy  of  consti- 
tution of  an  electron  is  a  definite  and  known  quantity;  it 
is  an  aggregation  of  energy  which  occurs  naturally  in  all 
parts  of  the  universe.  But  there  is  no  particular  duration 
of  time  associated  with  it  that  we  are  aware  of,  and  so  it 


THE  ATOM  OF  ACTION  183 

does  not  suggest  to  us  any  particular  lump  of  action. 
We  must  turn  to  a  form  of  energy  which  has  a  definite 
and  discoverable  period  of  time  associated  with  it,  such 
as  a  train  of  light-waves;  these  carry  with  them  a  unit 
of  time,  namely,  the  period  of  their  vibration.  The 
yellow  light  from  sodium  consists  of  aethereal  vibrations 
of  period  510  billions  to  the  second.  At  first  sight  we 
seem  to  be  faced  with  the  converse  difficulty;  we  have 
now  our  definite  period  of  time;  but  how  are  we  to  cut 
up  into  natural  units  the  energy  coming  from  a  sodium 
flame?  We  should,  of  course,  single  out  the  light  pro- 
ceeding from  a  single  atom,  but  this  will  not  break  up 
into  units  unless  the  atom  emits  light  discontinuously. 

It  turns  out  that  the  atom  does  emit  light  discontin- 
uously. It  sends  out  a  long  train  of  waves  and  then 
stops.  It  has  to  be  restarted  by  some  kind  of  stimula- 
tion before  it  emits  again.  We  do  not  perceive  this 
intermittence  in  an  ordinary  beam  of  light,  because  there 
are  myriads  of  atoms  engaged  in  the  production. 

The  amount  of  energy  coming  away  from  the  sodium 
atom  during  any  one  of  these  discontinuous  emissions 
is  found  to  be  3-4.  io-12  ergs.  This  energy  is,  as  we 
have  seen,  marked  by  a  distinctive  period  1-9.  io~15  sees. 
We  have  thus  the  two  ingredients  necessary  for  a 
natural  lump  of  action.  Multiply  them  together,  and 
we  obtain  6-55.  io~27  erg-seconds.  That  is  the  quan- 
tity h. 

The  remarkable  law  of  Nature  is  that  we  are  con- 
tinually getting  the  same  numerical  results.  We  may 
take  another  source  of  light — hydrogen,  calcium,  or  any 
other  atom.  The  energy  will  be  a  different  number  of 
ergs;  the  period  will  be  a  different  number  of  seconds; 
but  the  product  will  be  the  same  number  of  erg-seconds. 
The  same  applies  to  X-rays,  to  gamma  rays  and  to  other 


1 84  THE  QUANTUM  THEORY 

forms  of  radiation.  It  applies  to  light  absorbed  by  an 
atom  as  well  as  to  light  emitted,  the  absorption  being 
discontinuous  also.  Evidently  h  is  a  kind  of  atom — 
something  which  coheres  as  one  unit  in  the  processes  of 
radiation;  it  is  not  an  atom  of  matter  but  an  atom  or, 
as  we  usually  call  it,  a  quantum  of  the  more  elusive 
entity  action.  Whereas  there  are  92  different  kinds  of 
material  atoms  there  is  only  one  quantum  of  action — 
the  same  whatever  the  material  it  is  associated  with. 
I  say  the  same  without  reservation.  You  might  perhaps 
think  that  there  must  be  some  qualitative  difference 
between  the  quantum  of  red  light  and  the  quantum  of 
blue  light,  although  both  contain  the  same  number  of 
erg-seconds;  but  the  apparent  difference  is  only  relative 
to  a  frame  of  space  and  time  and  does  not  concern  the 
absolute  lump  of  action.  By  approaching  the  light- 
source  at  high  speed  we  change  the  red  light  to  blue 
light  in  accordance  with  Doppler's  principle;  the  energy 
of  the  waves  is  also  changed  by  being  referred  to  a 
new  frame  of  reference.  A  sodium  flame  and  a  hydro- 
gen flame  are  throwing  out  at  us  the  same  lumps  of 
action,  only  these  lumps  are  rather  differently  orientated 
with  respect  to  the  Now  lines  which  we  have  drawn 
across  the  four-dimensional  world.  If  we  change  our 
motion  so  as  to  alter  the  direction  of  the  Now  lines, 
we  can  see  the  lumps  of  sodium  origin  under  the  same 
orientation  in  which  we  formerly  saw  the  lumps  of 
hydrogen  origin  and  recognise  that  they  are  actually  the 
same. 

We  noticed  in  chapter  iv  that  the  shuffling  of  energy 
can  become  complete,  so  that  a  definite  state  is  reached 
known  as  thermodynamical  equilibrium;  and  we  re- 
marked that  this  is  only  possible  if  indivisible  units  are 
being  shuffled.     If  the  cards  can  be  torn  into  smaller  and 


CONFLICT  WITH  WAVE-THEORY  185 

smaller  pieces  without  limit  there  is  no  end  to  the 
process  of  shuffling.  The  indivisible  units  in  the  shuf- 
fling of  energy  are  the  quanta.  By  radiation  absorp- 
tion and  scattering  energy  is  shuffled  among  the  different 
receptacles  in  matter  and  aether,  but  only  a  whole 
quantum  passes  at  each  step.  It  was  in  fact  this  definite- 
ness  of  thermodynamical  equilibrium  which  first  put 
Prof.  Max  Planck  on  the  track  of  the  quantum;  and  the 
magnitude  of  h  was  first  calculated  by  analysis  of  the 
observed  composition  of  the  radiation  in  the  final  state 
of  randomness.  Progress  of  the  theory  in  its  adolescent 
stage  was  largely  due  to  Einstein  so  far  as  concerns  the 
general  principles  and  to  Bohr  as  regards  its  connection 
with  atomic  structure. 

The  paradoxical  nature  of  the  quantum  is  that 
although  it  is  indivisible  it  does  not  hang  together.  We 
examined  first  a  case  in  which  a  quantity  of  energy  was 
obviously  cohering  together,  viz.  an  electron,  but  we  did 
not  find  h;  then  we  turned  our  attention  to  a  case  in  which 
the  energy  was  obviously  dissolving  away  through  space, 
viz.  light-waves,  and  immediately  h  appeared.  The 
atom  of  action  seems  to  have  no  coherence  in  space; 
it  has  a  unity  which  overleaps  space.  How  can  such  a 
unity  be  made  to  appear  in  our  picture  of  a  world 
extended  through  space  and  time? 

Conflict  with  the  Wave-Theory  of  Light.  The  pursuit  of 
the  quantum  leads  to  many  surprises;  but  probably  none 
is  more  outrageous  to  our  preconceptions  than  the 
regathering  of  light  and  other  radiant  energy  into 
A-units,  when  all  the  classical  pictures  show  it  to  be 
dispersing  more  and  more.  Consider  the  light-waves 
which  are  the  result  of  a  single  emission  by  a  single  atom 
on  the  star  Sirius.    These  bear  away  a  certain  amount  of 


1 86  THE  QUANTUM  THEORY 

energy  endowed  with  a  certain  period,  and  the  product 
of  the  two  is  //.  The  period  is  carried  by  the  waves 
without  change,  but  the  energy  spreads  out  in  an  ever- 
widening  circle.  Eight  years  and  nine  months  after  the 
emission  the  wave-front  is  due  to  reach  the  earth.  A 
few  minutes  before  the  arrival  some  person  takes  it  into 
his  head  to  go  out  and  admire  the  glories  of  the  heavens 
and — in  short — to  stick  his  eye  in  the  way.  The  light- 
waves when  they  started  could  have  had  no  notion  what 
they  were  going  to  hit;  for  all  they  knew  they  were 
bound  on  a  journey  through  endless  space,  as  most  of 
their  colleagues  were.  Their  energy  would  seem  to  be 
dissipated  beyond  recovery  over  a  sphere  of  50  billion 
miles'  radius.  And  yet  if  that  energy  is  ever  to  enter 
matter  again,  if  it  is  to  work  those  chemical  changes  in 
the  retina  which  give  rise  to  the  sensation  of  light,  it 
must  enter  as  a  single  quantum  of  action  h.  Just 
6-55. 1  o-27  erg-seconds  must  enter  or  none  at  all.  Just 
as  the  emitting  atom  regardless  of  all  laws  of  classical 
physics  is  determined  that  whatever  goes  out  of  it  shall 
be  just  /*,  so  the  receiving  atom  is  determined  that  what- 
ever comes  into  it  shall  be  just  h.  Not  all  the  light- 
waves pass  by  without  entering  the  eye;  for  somehow 
we  are  able  to  see  Sirius.  How  is  it  managed?  Do  the 
ripples  striking  the  eye  send  a  message  round  to  the 
back  part  of  the  wave,  saying,  "We  have  found  an  eye. 
Let's  all  crowd  into  it!" 

Attempts  to  account  for  this  phenomenon  follow  two 
main  devices  which  we  may  describe  as  the  "collection- 
box"  theory  and  the  "sweepstake"  theory,  respectively. 
Making  no  effort  to  translate  them  into  scientific 
language,  they  amount  to  this:  In  the  first  the  atom 
holds  a  collection-box  into  which  each  arriving  group 
of   waves   pays    a    very    small    contribution;    when    the 


CONFLICT  WITH  WAVE-THEORY  187 

amount  in  the  box  reaches  a  whole  quantum,  it  enters 
the  atom.  In  the  second  the  atom  uses  the  small  frac- 
tion of  a  quantum  offered  to  it  to  buy  a  ticket  in  a 
sweepstake  in  which  the  prizes  are  whole  quanta;  some 
of  the  atoms  will  win  whole  quanta  which  they  can 
absorb,  and  it  is  these  winning  atoms  in  our  retina 
which  tell  us  of  the  existence  of  Sirius. 

The    collection-box    explanation    is    not    tenable.      As 
Jeans    once    said,    not    only   does    the    quantum    theory 
forbid  us  to  kill  two  birds  with  one  stone;  it  will  not 
even  let  us  kill  one  bird  with  two  stones.     I  cannot  go 
fully    into    the    reasons    against    this    theory,    but    may 
illustrate   one   or   two   of   the   difficulties.      One   serious 
difficulty    would    arise    from    the    half-filled    collection- 
boxes.      We   shall   see    this   more    easily   if,    instead   of 
atoms,    we    consider   molecules  which   also    absorb    only 
full    quanta.      A   molecule    might   begin   to    collect    the 
various  kinds  of  light  which  it  can  absorb,  but  before  it 
has  collected  a  quantum  of  any  one  kind  it  takes  part 
in   a   chemical   reaction.      New  compounds    are    formed 
which  no  longer  absorb  the  old  kinds  of  light;  they  have 
entirely  different  absorption  spectra.     They  would  have 
to    start   afresh   to   collect   the   corresponding   kinds   of 
light.     What  is  to  be  done  with  the  old  accumulations 
now  useless,  since  they  can  never  be  completed?     One 
thing  is  certain;  they  are  not  tipped  out  into  the  aether 
when  the  chemical  change  occurs. 

A  phenomenon  which  seems  directly  opposed  to  any 
kind  of  collection-box  explanation  is  the  photoelectric 
effect.  When  light  shines  on  metallic  films  of  sodium, 
potassium,  rubidium,  etc.,  free  electrons  are  discharged 
from  the  film.  They  fly  away  at  high  speed,  and  it  is 
possible  to  measure  experimentally  their  speed  or 
energy.      Undoubtedly    it    is    the    incident    light    which 


188  THE  QUANTUM  THEORY 

provides  the  energy  of  these  explosions,  but  the  phe- 
nomenon is  governed  by  a  remarkable  rule.  Firstly,  the 
speed  of  the  electrons  is  not  increased  by  using  more 
powerful  light.  Concentration  of  the  light  produces 
more  explosions  but  not  more  powerful  explosions. 
Secondly,  the  speed  is  increased  by  using  bluer  light,  i.e. 
light  of  shorter  period.  For  example,  the  feeble  light 
reaching  us  from  Sirius  will  cause  more  powerful  ejec- 
tions of  electrons  than  full  sunlight,  because  Sirius  is 
bluer  than  the  sun;  the  remoteness  of  Sirius  does  not 
weaken  the  ejections  though  it  reduces  their  number. 

This  is  a  straightforward  quantum  phenomenon. 
Every  electron  flying  out  of  the  metal  has  picked  up  just 
one  quantum  from  the  incident  light.  Since  the  /z-rule 
associates  the  greater  energy  with  the  shorter  vibration 
period,  bluer  light  gives  the  more  intense  energy. 
Experiments  show  that  (after  deducting  a  constant 
"threshold"  energy  used  up  in  extricating  the  electron 
from  the  film)  each  electron  comes  out  with  a  kinetic 
energy  equal  to  the  energy  of  the  quantum  of  incident 
light. 

The  film  can  be  prepared  in  the  dark;  but  on  ex- 
posure to  feeble  light  electrons  immediately  begin  to 
fly  out  before  any  of  the  collection-boxes  could  have 
been  filled  by  fair  means.  Nor  can  we  appeal  to  any 
trigger  action  of  the  light  releasing  an  electron  already 
loaded  up  with  energy  for  its  journey;  it  is  the  nature 
of  the  light  which  settles  the  amount  of  the  load.  The 
light  calls  the  tune,  therefore  the  light  must  pay  the 
piper.  Only  classical  theory  does  not  provide  light  with 
a  pocket  to  pay  from. 

It  is  always  difficult  to  make  a  fence  of  objections  so 
thorough  as  to  rule  out  all  progress  along  a  certain  line 
of  explanation.     But  even  if  it  is  still  possible  to  wriggle 


CONFLICT  WITH  WAVE-THEORY  189 

on,  there  comes  a  time  when  one  begins  to  perceive  that 
the  evasions  are  far-fetched.  If  we  have  any  instinct 
that  can  recognise  a  fundamental  law  of  Nature  when 
it  sees  one,  that  instinct  tells  us  that  the  interaction  of 
radiation  and  matter  in  single  quanta  is  something  lying 
at  the  root  of  world-structure  and  not  a  casual  detail  in 
the  mechanism  of  the  atom.  Accordingly  we  turn  to  the 
"sweepstake"  theory,  which  sees  in  this  phenomenon  a 
starting-point  for  a  radical  revision  of  the  classical  con- 
ceptions. 

Suppose  that  the  light-waves  are  of  such  intensity  that, 
according  to  the  usual  reckoning  of  their  energy,  one- 
millionth  of  a  quantum  is  brought  within  range  of  each 
atom.  The  unexpected  phenomenon  is  that  instead  of 
each  atom  absorbing  one-millionth  of  a  quantum,  one 
atom  out  of  every  million  absorbs  a  whole  quantum. 
That  whole  quanta  are  absorbed  is  shown  by  the  photo- 
electric experiments  already  described,  since  each  of  the 
issuing  electrons  has  managed  to  secure  the  energy  of  a 
whole  quantum. 

It  would  seem  that  what  the  light-waves  were  really 
bearing  within  reach  of  each  atom  was  not  a  millionth 
of  a  quantum  but  a  millionth  chance  of  securing  a  whole 
quantum.  The  wave-theory  of  light  pictures  and 
describes  something  evenly  distributed  over  the  whole 
wave-front  which  has  usually  been  identified  with  energy. 
Owing  to  well-established  phenomena  such  as  interfer- 
ence and  diffraction  it  seems  impossible  to  deny  this  uni- 
formity, but  we  must  give  it  another  interpretation;  it 
is  a  uniform  chance  of  energy.  Following  the  rather 
old-fashioned  definition  of  energy  as  "capacity  for  doing 
work"  the  waves  carry  over  their  whole  front  a  uniform 
chance  of  doing  work.  It  is  the  propagation  of  a  chance 
which  the  wave-theory  studies. 


190  THE  QUANTUM  THEORY 

Different  views  may  be  held  as  to  how  the  prize- 
drawing  is  conducted  on  the  sweepstake  theory.  Some 
hold  that  the  lucky  part  of  the  wave-front  is  already 
marked  before  the  atom  is  reached.  In  addition  to  the 
propagation  of  uniform  waves  the  propagation  of  a 
photon  or  "ray  of  luck"  is  involved.  This  seems  to  me 
out  of  keeping  with  the  general  trend  of  the  modern 
quantum  theory;  and  although  most  authorities  now  take 
this  view,  which  is  said  to  be  indicated  definitely  by 
certain  experiments,  I  do  not  place  much  reliance  on  the 
stability  of  this  opinion. 

Theory  of  the  Atom.  We  return  now  to  further  experi- 
mental knowledge  of  quanta.  The  mysterious  quantity 
h  crops  up  inside  the  atom  as  well  as  outside  it.  Let  us 
take  the  simplest  of  all  atoms,  namely,  the  hydrogen 
atom.  This  consists  of  a  proton  and  an  electron,  that  is 
to  say  a  unit  charge  of  positive  electricity  and  a  unit 
charge  of  negative  electricity.  The  proton  carries  nearly 
all  the  mass  of  the  atom  and  remains  rock-like  at  the 
centre,  whilst  the  nimble  electron  moves  round  in  a 
circular  or  elliptic  orbit  under  the  inverse  square-law 
of  attraction  between  them.  The  system  is  thus  very 
like  a  sun  and  a  planet.  But  whereas  in  the  solar  system 
the  planet's  orbit  may  be  of  any  size  and  any  eccentricity, 
the  electron's  orbit  is  restricted  to  a  definite  series  of 
sizes  and  shapes.  There  is  nothing  in  the  classical 
theory  of  electromagnetism  to  impose  such  a  restriction; 
but  the  restriction  exists,  and  the  law  imposing  it  has 
been  discovered.  It  arises  because  the  atom  is  arranging 
to  make  something  in  its  interior  equal  to  h.  The  inter- 
mediate orbits  are  excluded  because  they  would  involve 
fractions  of  /*,  and  h  cannot  be  divided. 

But  there   is   one   relaxation.      When   wave-energy  is 


THEORY  OF  THE  ATOM  191 

sent  out  from  or  taken  into  the  atom,  the  amount  and 
period  must  correspond  exactly  to  h.  But  as  regards 
its  internal  arrangements  the  atom  has  no  objection  to 
2/*,  3/*,  4/i,  etc.;  it  only  insists  that  fractions  shall  be 
excluded.  That  is  why  there  are  many  alternative  orbits 
for  the  electron  corresponding  to  different  integral  mul- 
tipliers of  h.  We  call  these  multipliers  quantum  num- 
bers, and  speak  of  1 -quantum  orbits,  2-quantum  orbits, 
etc.  I  will  not  enter  here  into  the  exact  definition  of 
what  it  is  that  has  to  be  an  exact  multiple  of  h;  but  it 
is  something  which,  viewed  in  the  four-dimensional 
world,  is  at  once  seen  to  be  action  though  this  may  not 
be  so  apparent  when  we  view  it  in  the  ordinary  way  in 
three-dimensional  sections.  Also  several  features  of  the 
atom  are  regulated  independently  by  this  rule,  and 
accordingly  there  are  several  quantum  numbers — one  for 
each  feature;  but  to  avoid  technical  complication  I  shall 
refer  only  to  the  quantum  numbers  belonging  to  one 
leading  feature. 

According  to  this  picture  of  the  atom,  which  is  due 
to  Niels  Bohr,  the  only  possible  change  of  state  is  the 
transfer  of  an  electron  from  one  quantum  orbit  to 
another.  Such  a  jump  must  occur  whenever  light  is 
absorbed  or  emitted.  Suppose  then  that  an  electron  which 
has  been  travelling  in  one  of  the  higher  orbits  jumps 
down  into  an  orbit  of  less  energy.  The  atom  will  then 
have  a  certain  amount  of  surplus  energy  that  must  be  got 
rid  of.  The  lump  of  energy  is  fixed,  and  it  remains  to 
settle  the  period  of  vibration  that  it  shall  have  when  it 
changes  into  aether-waves.  It  seems  incredible  that  the 
atom  should  get  hold  of  the  aether  and  shake  it  in  any 
other  period  than  one  of  those  in  which  it  is  itself 
vibrating.  Yet  it  is  the  experimental  fact  that,  when  the 
atom    by    radiating    sets    the    aether    in    vibration,    the 


192  THE  QUANTUM  THEORY 

periods  of  its  electronic  circulation  are  ignored  and  the 
period  of  the  aether-waves  is  settled  not  by  any  pictur- 
able  mechanism  but  by  the  seemingly  artificial  h-rulc.  It 
would  seem  that  the  atom  carelessly  throws  overboard 
a  lump  of  energy  which,  as  it  glides  into  the  aether, 
moulds  itself  into  a  quantum  of  action  by  taking  on  the 
period  required  to  make  the  product  of  energy  and 
period  equal  to  h.  If  this  unmechanical  process  of  emis- 
sion seems  contrary  to  our  preconceptions,  the  exactly 
converse  process  of  absorption  is  even  more  so.  Here 
the  atom  has  to  look  out  for  a  lump  of  energy  of  the 
exact  amount  required  to  raise  an  electron  to  the  higher 
orbit.  It  can  only  extract  such  a  lump  from  aether- 
waves  of  particular  period — not  a  period  which  has 
resonance  with  the  structure  of  the  atom,  but  the  period 
which  makes  the  energy  into  an  exact  quantum. 

As  the  adjustment  between  the  energy  of  the  orbit  jump 
and  the  period  of  the  light  carrying  away  that  energy  so 
as  to  give  the  constant  quantity  h  is  perhaps  the  most 
striking  evidence  of  the  dominance  of  the  quantum,  it 
will  be  worth  while  to  explain  how  the  energy  of  an 
orbit  jump  in  an  atom  can  be  measured.  It  is  possible  to 
impart  to  a  single  electron  a  known  amount  of  energy  by 
making  it  travel  along  an  electric  field  with  a  measured 
drop  of  potential.  If  this  projectile  hits  an  atom  it  may 
cause  one  of  the  electrons  circulating  in  the  atom  to 
jump  to  an  upper  orbit,  but,  of  course,  only  if  its  energy 
is  sufficient  to  supply  that  required  for  the  jump;  if  the 
electron  has  too  little  energy  it  can  do  nothing  and  must 
pass  on  with  its  energy  intact.  Let  us  fire  a  stream  of 
electrons  all  endowed  with  the  same  known  energy 
into  the  midst  of  a  group  of  atoms.  If  the  energy  is 
below  that  corresponding  to  an  orbit  jump,  the  stream 
will    pass     through    without    interference    other    than 


CLASSICAL  AND  QUANTUM  LAWS  193 

ordinary  scattering.  Now  gradually  increase  the  energy 
of  the  electrons;  quite  suddenly  we  find  that  the  electrons 
are  leaving  a  great  deal  of  their  energy  behind.  That 
means  that  the  critical  energy  has  been  reached  and 
orbit  jumps  are  being  excited.  Thus  we  have  a  means 
of  measuring  the  critical  energy  which  is  just  that  of  the 
jump — the  difference  of  energy  of  the  two  states  of  the 
atom.  This  method  of  measurement  has  the  advantage 
that  it  does  not  involve  any  knowledge  of  the  constant  h, 
so  that  there  is  no  fear  of  a  vicious  circle  when  we  use 
the  measured  energies  to  test  the  h  rule.*  Incidentally 
this  experiment  provides  another  argument  against  the 
collection-box  theory.  Small  contributions  of  energy  are 
not  thankfully  received,  and  electrons  which  offer  any- 
thing less  than  the  full  contribution  for  a  jump  are  not 
allowed  to  make  any  payment  at  all. 

Relation  of  Classical  Laws  to  Quantum  Laws.  To  fol- 
low up  the  verification  and  successful  application  of  the 
quantum  laws  would  lead  to  a  detailed  survey  of  the 
greater  part  of  modern  physics — specific  heats,  mag- 
netism, X-rays,  radioactivity,  and  so  on.  We  must  leave 
this  and  return  to  a  general  consideration  of  the  rela- 
tion between  classical  laws  and  quantum  laws.  For  at 
least  fifteen  years  we  have  used  classical  laws  and  quan- 
tum laws  alongside  one  another  notwithstanding  the 
irreconcilability  of  their  conceptions.  In  the  model  atom 
the  electrons  are  supposed  to  traverse  their  orbits  under 
the  classical  laws  of  electrodynamics;  but  they  jump 
from  one  orbit  to  another  in  a  way  entirely  incon- 
sistent with    those    laws.      The    energies    of    the    orbits 

*  Since  the  h  rule  is  now  well  established  the  energies  of  different 
states  of  the  atoms  are  usually  calculated  by  its  aid;  to  use  these  to  test 
the  rule  would  be  a  vicious  circle. 


194  THE  QUANTUM  THEORY 

in  hydrogen  are  calculated  by  classical  laws;  but  one 
of  the  purposes  of  the  calculation  is  to  verify  the 
association  of  energy  and  period  in  the  unit  /*,  which  is 
contrary  to  classical  laws  of  radiation.  The  whole 
procedure  is  glaringly  contradictory  but  conspicuously 
successful. 

In  my  observatory  there  is  a  telescope  which  con- 
denses the  light  of  a  star  on  a  film  of  sodium  in  a  photo- 
electric cell.  I  rely  on  the  classical  theory  to  conduct 
the  light  through  the  lenses  and  focus  it  in  the  cell;  then 
I  switch  on  to  the  quantum  theory  to  make  the  light 
fetch  out  electrons  from  the  sodium  film  to  be  collected 
in  an  electrometer.  If  I  happen  to  transpose  the  two 
theories,  the  quantum  theory  convinces  me  that  the  light 
will  never  get  concentrated  in  the  cell  and  the  classical 
theory  shows  that  it  is  powerless  to  extract  the  elec- 
trons if  it  does  get  in.  I  have  no  logical  reason  for 
not  using  the  theories  this  way  round;  only  experience 
teaches  me  that  I  must  not.  Sir  William  Bragg  was  not 
overstating  the  case  when  he  said  that  we  use  the  classi- 
cal theory  on  Mondays,  Wednesday  and  Fridays,  and 
the  quantum  theory  on  Tuesdays,  Thursdays  and  Satur- 
days. Perhaps  that  ought  to  make  us  feel  a  little  sym- 
pathetic towards  the  man  whose  philosophy  of  the  uni- 
verse takes  one  form  on  weekdays  and  another  form  on 
Sundays. 

In  the  last  century — and  I  think  also  in  this — there 
must  have  been  many  scientific  men  who  kept  their 
science  and  religion  in  watertight  compartments.  One 
set  of  beliefs  held  good  in  the  laboratory  and  another  set 
of  beliefs  in  church,  and  no  serious  effort  was  made  to 
harmonise  them.  The  attitude  is  defensible.  To  discuss 
the  compatibility  of  the  beliefs  would  lead  the  scientist 
into  regions  of  thought  in  which  he  was  inexpert;  and 
any  answer   he   might   reach  would  be   undeserving  of 


CLASSICAL  AND  QUANTUM  LAWS  195 

strong  confidence.  Better  admit  that  there  was  some 
truth  both  in  science  and  religion;  and  if  they  must  fight, 
let  it  be  elsewhere  than  in  the  brain  of  a  hard-working 
scientist.  If  we  have  ever  scorned  this  attitude,  Nemesis 
has  overtaken  us.  For  ten  years  we  have  had  to  divide 
modern  science  into  two  compartments;  we  have  one  set 
of  beliefs  in  the  classical  compartment  and  another  set 
of  beliefs  in  the  quantum  compartment.  Unfortunately 
our  compartments  are  not  watertight. 

We  must,  of  course,  look  forward  to  an  ultimate 
reconstruction  of  our  conceptions  of  the  physical  world 
which  will  embrace  both  the  classical  laws  and  the 
quantum  laws  in  harmonious  association.  There  are  still 
some  who  think  that  the  reconciliation  will  be  effected 
by  a  development  of  classical  conceptions.  But  the 
physicists  of  what  I  may  call  "the  Copenhagen  school" 
believe  that  the  reconstruction  has  to  start  at  the  other 
end,  and  that  in  the  quantum  phenomena  we  are  getting 
down  to  a  more  intimate  contact  with  Nature's  way  of 
working  than  in  the  coarse-grained  experience  which 
has  furnished  the  classical  laws.  The  classical  school 
having  become  convinced  of  the  existence  of  these  uni- 
form lumps  of  action,  speculates  on  the  manufacture  of 
the  chopper  necessary  to  carve  off  uniform  lumps;  the 
Copenhagen  school  on  the  other  hand  sees  in  these 
phenomena  the  insubstantial  pageant  of  space,  time  and 
matter  crumbling  into  grains  of  action.  I  do  not  think 
that  the  Copenhagen  school  has  been  mainly  influenced 
by  the  immense  difficulty  of  constructing  a  satisfactory 
chopper  out  of  classical  material;  its  view  arises  espe- 
cially from  a  study  of  the  meeting  point  of  quantum  and 
classical  laws. 

The  classical  laws  are  the  limit  to  which  the  quantum 
laws  tend  when  states  of  very  high  quantum  number  are 
concerned. 


i96  THE  QUANTUM  THEORY 

This  is  the  famous  Correspondence  Principle  enun- 
ciated by  Bohr.  It  was  at  first  a  conjecture  based  on 
rather  slight  hints;  but  as  our  knowledge  of  quantum 
laws  has  grown,  it  has  been  found  that  when  we  apply 
them  to  states  of  very  high  quantum  number  they  con- 
verge to  the  classical  laws,  and  predict  just  what  the 
classical  laws  would  predict. 

For  an  example,  take  a  hydrogen  atom  with  its  elec- 
tron in  a  circular  orbit  of  very  high  quantum  number, 
that  is  to  say  far  away  from  the  proton.  On  Monday, 
Wednesday  and  Friday  it  is  governed  by  classical  laws. 
These  say  that  it  must  emit  a  feeble  radiation  continu- 
ously, of  strength  determined  by  the  acceleration  it  is 
undergoing  and  of  period  agreeing  with  its  own  period 
of  revolution.  Owing  to  the  gradual  loss  of  energy  it 
will  spiral  down  towards  the  proton.  On  Tuesday, 
Thursday  and  Saturday  it  is  governed  by  quantum  laws 
and  jumps  from  one  orbit  to  another.  There  is  a 
quantum  law  that  I  have  not  mentioned  which  prescribes 
that  (for  circular  orbits  only)  the  jump  must  always  be 
to  the  circular  orbit  next  lower,  so  that  the  electron 
comes  steadily  down  the  series  of  steps  without  skipping 
any.  Another  law  prescribes  the  average  time  between 
each  jump  and  therefore  the  average  time  between  the 
successive  emissions  of  light.  The  small  lumps  of 
energy  cast  away  at  each  step  form  light-waves  of  period 
determined  by  the  h  rule. 

"Preposterous!  You  cannot  seriously  mean  that  the 
electron  does  different  things  on  different  days  of  the 
week!" 

But  did  I  say  that  it  does  different  things?  I  used 
different  words  to  describe  its  doings.  I  run  down  the 
stairs  on  Tuesday  and  slide  down  the  banisters  on 
Wednesday;  but  if  the  staircase  consists  of  innumerable 


CLASSICAL  AND  QUANTUM  LAWS  197 

infinitesimal  steps,  there  is  no  essential  difference  in 
my  mode  of  progress  on  the  two  days.  And  so  it  makes 
no  difference  whether  the  electron  steps  from  one  orbit 
to  the  next  lower  or  comes  down  in  a  spiral  when  the 
number  of  steps  is  innumerably  great.  The  succession 
of  lumps  of  energy  cast  overboard  merges  into  a  con- 
tinuous outflow.  If  you  had  the  formulae  before  you, 
you  would  find  that  the  period  of  the  light  and  the 
strength  of  radiation  are  the  same  whether  calculated  by 
the  Monday  or  the  Tuesday  method — but  only  when 
the  quantum  number  is  infinitely  great.  The  disagree- 
ment is  not  very  serious  when  the  number  is  moderately 
large;  but  for  small  quantum  numbers  the  atom  cannot 
sit  on  the  fence.  It  has  to  decide  between  Monday 
(classical)  and  Tuesday  (quantum)  rules.  It  chooses 
Tuesday  rules. 

If,  as  we  believe,  this  example  is  typical,  it  indicates 
one  direction  which  the  reconstruction  of  ideas  must 
take.  We  must  not  try  to  build  up  from  classical  con- 
ceptions, because  the  classical  laws  only  become  true  and 
the  conceptions  concerned  in  them  only  become  defined 
in  the  limiting  case  when  the  quantum  numbers  of  the 
system  are  very  large.  We  must  start  from  new  con- 
ceptions appropriate  to  low  as  well  as  to  high  numbered 
states;  out  of  these  the  classical  conceptions  should 
emerge,  first  indistinctly,  then  definitely,  as  the  number 
of  the  state  increases,  and  the  classical  laws  become 
more  and  more  nearly  true.  "  I  cannot  foretell  the  result 
of  this  remodelling,  but  presumably  room  must  be 
found  for  a  conception  of  "states",  the  unity  of  a 
state  replacing  the  kind  of  tie  expressed  by  classical 
forces.  For  low  numbered  states  the  current  vocabulary 
of  physics  is  inappropriate;  at  the  moment  we  can 
scarcely  avoid  using  it,  but  the  present  contradictoriness 


1 98  THE  QUANTUM  THEORY 

of  our  theories  arises  from  this  misuse.  For  such  states 
space  and  time  do  not  exist — at  least  I  can  see  no  reason 
to  believe  that  they  do.  But  it  must  be  supposed  that 
when  high  numbered  states  are  considered  there  will 
be  found  in  the  new  scheme  approximate  counterparts 
of  the  space  and  time  of  current  conception — some- 
thing ready  to  merge  into  space  and  time  when  the 
state  numbers  are  infinite.  And  simultaneously  the  inter- 
actions described  by  transitions  of  states  will  merge 
into  classical  forces  exerted  across  space  and  time.  So 
that  in  the  limit  the  classical  description  becomes  an 
available  alternative.  Now  in  practical  experience  we 
have  generally  had  to  deal  with  systems  whose  ties  are 
comparatively  loose  and  correspond  to  very  high  quan- 
tum numbers;  consequently  our  first  survey  of  the 
world  has  stumbled  across  the  classical  laws  and  our 
present  conceptions  of  the  world  consist  of  those  enti- 
ties which  only  take  definite  shape  for  high  quantum 
numbers.  But  in  the  interior  of  the  atom  and  molecule, 
in  the  phenomena  of  radiation,  and  probably  also  in  the 
constitution  of  very  dense  stars  such  as  the  Companion 
of  Sirius,  the  state  numbers  are  not  high  enough  to 
admit  this  treatment.  These  phenomena  are  now  forcing 
us  back  to  the  more  fundamental  conceptions  out  of 
which  the  classical  conceptions  (sufficient  for  the  other 
types  of  phenomena)  ought  to  emerge  as  one  extreme 
limit. 

For  an  example  I  will  borrow  a  quantum  conception 
from  the  next  chapter.  It  may  not  be  destined  to  sur- 
vive in  the  present  rapid  evolution  of  ideas,  but  at  any 
rate  it  will  illustrate  my  point.  In  Bohr's  semi-classical 
model  of  the  hydrogen  atom  there  is  an  electron  de- 
scribing a  circular  or  elliptic  orbit.  This  is  only  a  model; 
the   real  atom  contains  nothing  of  the  sort.     The   real 


CLASSICAL  AND  QUANTUM  LAWS  199 

atom  contains  something  which  it  has  not  entered  into 
the  mind  of  man  to  conceive,  which  has,  however,  been 
described  symbolically  by  Schrodinger.  This  "some- 
thing" is  spread  about  in  a  manner  by  no  means  com- 
parable to  an  electron  describing  an  orbit.  Now  excite 
the  atom  into  successively  higher  and  higher  quantum 
states.  In  the  Bohr  model  the  electron  leaps  into  higher 
and  higher  orbits.  In  the  real  atom  Schrodinger's 
"something"  begins  to  draw  itself  more  and  more 
together  until  it  begins  sketchily  to  outline  the  Bohr 
orbit  and  even  imitates  a  condensation  running  round. 
Go  on  to  still  higher  quantum  numbers,  and  Schro- 
dinger's  symbol  now  represents  a  compact  body  moving 
round  in  the  same  orbit  and  the  same  period  as  the 
electron  in  Bohr's  model,  and  moreover  radiating 
according  to  the  classical  laws  of  an  electron.  And  so 
when  the  quantum  number  reaches  infinity,  and  the 
atom  bursts,  a  genuine  classical  electron  flies  out.  The 
electron,  as  it  leaves  the  atom,  crystallises  out  of  Schro- 
dinger's  mist  like  a  genie  emerging  from  his  bottle. 


Chapter  X 

THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

The  conflict  between  quantum  theory  and  classical 
theory  becomes  especially  acute  in  the  problem  of  the 
propagation  of  light.  Here  in  effect  it  becomes  a  con- 
flict between  the  corpuscular  theory  of  light  and  the 
wave  theory. 

In  the  early  days  it  was  often  asked,  How  large  is  a 
quantum  of  light?  One  answer  is  obtained  by  examining 
a  star  image  formed  with  the  great  ioo-inch  reflector 
at  Mt.  Wilson.  The  diffraction  pattern  shows  that  each 
emission  from  each  atom  must  be  filling  the  whole  mir- 
ror. For  if  one  atom  illuminates  one  part  only  and 
another  atom  another  part  only,  we  ought  to  get  the 
same  effect  by  illuminating  different  parts  of  the  mirror 
by  different  stars  (since  there  is  no  particular  virtue  in 
using  atoms  from  the  same  star)  ;  actually  the  diffraction 
pattern  then  obtained  is  not  the  same.  The  quantum 
must  be  large  enough  to  cover  a   ioo-inch  mirror. 

But  if  this  same  star-light  without  any  artificial  con- 
centration falls  on  a  film  of  potassium,  electrons  will 
fly  out  each  with  the  whole  energy  of  a  quantum.  This 
is  not  a  trigger  action  releasing  energy  already  stored  in 
the  atom,  because  the  amount  of  energy  is  fixed  by  the 
nature  of  thi  light,  not  by  the  nature  of  the  atom.  A 
whole  quantum  of  light  energy  must  have  gone  into  the 
atom  and  blasted  away  the  electron.  The  quantum 
must  be  small  enough  to  enter  an  atom. 

I  do  not  think  there  is  much  doubt  as  to  the  ultimate 
origin  of  this  contradiction.  We  must  not  think  about 
space   and  time   in  connection  with   an   individual   quan- 

200 


WAVE-THEORY  OF  MATTER  201 

turn;  and  the  extension  of  a  quantum  in  space  has  no 
real  meaning.  To  apply  these  conceptions  to  a  single 
quantum  is  like  reading  the  Riot  Act  to  one  man.  A 
single  quantum  has  not  travelled  50  billion  miles  from 
Sirius;  it  has  not  been  8  years  on  the  way.  But  when 
enough  quanta  are  gathered  to  form  a  quorum  there 
will  be  found  among  them  statistical  properties  which 
are  the  genesis  of  the  50  billion  miles'  distance  of  Sirius 
and  the  8  years'  journey  of  the  light. 

Wave-Theory  of  Matter.  It  is  comparatively  easy  to 
realise  what  we  have  got  to  do.  It  is  much  more  diffi- 
cult to  start  to  do  it.  Before  we  review  the  attempts 
in  the  last  year  or  two  to  grapple  with  this  problem  we 
shall  briefly  consider  a  less  drastic  method  of  progress 
initiated  by  De  Broglie.  For  the  moment  we  shall  be 
content  to  accept  the  mystery  as  a  mystery.  Light,  we 
will  say,  is  an  entity  with  the  wave  property  of  spread- 
ing out  to  fill  the  largest  object  glass  and  with  all  the 
well-known  properties  of  diffraction  and  interference; 
simultaneously  it  is  an  entity  with  the  corpuscular  or 
bullet  property  of  expending  its  whole  energy  on  one 
very  small  target.  We  can  scarcely  describe  such  an 
entity  as  a  wave  or  as  a  particle;  perhaps  as  a  com- 
promise we  had  better  call  it  a  "wavicle". 

There  is  nothing  new  under  the  sun,  and  this  latest. 
volte-face  almost  brings  us  back  to  Newton's  theory  of 
light — a  curious  mixture  of  corpuscular  and  wave-theory. 
There  is  perhaps  a  pleasing  sentiment  in  this  "return 
to  Newton".  But  to  suppose  that  Newton's  scientific 
reputation  is  especially  vindicated  by  De  Broglie's 
theory  of  light,  is  as  absurd  as  to  suppose  that  it  is 
shattered  by  Einstein's  theory  of  gravitation.  There 
was  no  phenomenon  known  to  Newton  which  could  not 


202      THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

be  amply  covered  by  the  wave-theory;  and  the  clearing 
away  of  false  evidence  for  a  partly  corpuscular  theory, 
which  influenced  Newton,  is  as  much  a  part  of  scientific 
progress  as  the  bringing  forward  of  the  (possibly)  true 
evidence,  which  influences  us  to-day.  To  imagine  that 
Newton's  great  scientific  reputation  is  tossing  up  and 
down  in  these  latter-day  revolutions  is  to  confuse  science 
with   omniscience. 

To  return  to  the  wavicle. — If  that  which  we  have 
commonly  regarded  as  a  wave  partakes  also  of  the 
nature  of  a  particle,  may  not  that  which  we  have  com- 
monly regarded  as  a  particle  partake  also  of  the  nature 
of  a  wave?  It  was  not  until  the  present  century  that 
experiments  were  tried  of  a  kind  suitable  to  bring  out 
the  corpuscular  aspect  of  the  nature  of  light;  perhaps 
experiments  may  still  be  possible  which  will  bring  out 
a  wave  aspect  of  the  nature  of  an  electron. 

So,  as  a  first  step,  instead  of  trying  to  clear  up  the 
mystery  we  try  to  extend  it.  Instead  of  explaining  how 
anything  can  possess  simultaneously  the  incongruous 
properties  of  wave  and  particle  we  seek  to  show  experi- 
mentally that  these  properties  are  universally  associated. 
There  are  no  pure  waves  and  no  pure  particles. 

The  characteristic  of  a  wave-theory  is  the  spreading 
of  a  ray  of  light  after  passing  through  a  narrow  aper- 
ture— a  well-known  phenomenon  called  diffraction.  The 
scale  of  the  phenomenon  is  proportional  to  the  wave- 
length of  the  light.  De  Broglie  has  shown  us  how  to 
calculate  the  lengths  of  the  waves  (if  any)  associated 
with  an  electron,  i.e.  considering  it  to  be  no  longer  a  pure 
particle  but  a  wavicle.  It  appears  that  in  some  circum- 
stances the  scale  of  the  corresponding  diffraction  effects 
will  not  be  too  small  for  experimental  detection.  There 
are   now   a   number   of   experimental   results   quoted   as 


WAVE-THEORY  OF  MATTER  203 

verifying  this  prediction.  I  scarcely  know  whether  they 
are  yet  to  be  considered  conclusive,  but  there  does  seem 
to  be  serious  evidence  that  in  the  scattering  of  electrons 
by  atoms  phenomena  occur  which  would  not  be  pro- 
duced according  to  the  usual  theory  that  electrons  are 
purely  corpuscular.  These  effects  analogous  to  the 
diffraction  and  interference  of  light  carry  us  into  the 
stronghold  of  the  wave-theory.  Long  ago  such  phe- 
nomena ruled  out  all  purely  corpuscular  theories  of 
light;  perhaps  to-day  we  are  finding  similar  phenomena 
which  will  rule  out  all  purely  corpuscular  theories  of 
matter.* 

A  similar  idea  was  entertained  in  a  "new  statistical 
mechanics"  developed  by  Einstein  and  Bose — at  least 
that  seems  to  be  the  physical  interpretation  of  the  highly 
abstract  mathematics  of  their  theory.  As  so  often  hap- 
pens the  change  from  the  classical  mechanics,  though 
far-reaching  in  principle,  gave  only  insignificant  cor- 
rections when  applied  to  ordinary  practical  problems. 
Significant  differences  could  only  be  expected  in  matter 
much  denser  than  anything  yet  discovered  or  imagined. 
Strange  to  say,  just  about  the  time  when  it  was  realised 
that  very  dense  matter  might  have  strange  properties 
different  from  those  expected  according  to  classical 
conceptions,  very  dense  matter  was  found  in  the  uni- 
verse. Astronomical  evidence  seems  to  leave  practically 
no  doubt  that  in  the  so-called  white  dwarf  stars  the 
density  of  matter  far  transcends  anything  of  which  we 
have  terrestrial  experience;  in  the  Companion  of  Sirius, 
for  example,  the  density  is  about  a  ton  to  the  cubic  inch. 
This  condition  is  explained  by  the  fact  that  the  high 
temperature    and    correspondingly    intense    agitation    of 

*The   evidence   is   much   stronger   now   than   when   the   lectures   were 
delivered. 


204      THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

the  material  breaks  up  (ionises)  the  outer  electron  sys- 
tems of  the  atoms,  so  that  the  fragments  can  be  packed 
much  more  closely  together.  At  ordinary  temperatures 
the  minute  nucleus  of  the  atom  is  guarded  by  outposts 
of  sentinel  electrons  which  ward  off  other  atoms  from 
close  approach  even  under  the  highest  pressures;  but  at 
stellar  temperatures  the  agitation  is  so  great  that  the 
electrons  leave  their  posts  and  run  all  over  the  place. 
Exceedingly  tight  packing  then  becomes  possible  under 
high  enough  pressure.  R.  H.  Fowler  has  found  that  in 
the  white  dwarf  stars  the  density  is  so  great  that  classi- 
cal methods  are  inadequate  and  the  new  statistical 
mechanics  must  be  used.  In  particular  he  has  in  this 
way  relieved  an  anxiety  which  had  been  felt  as  to  their 
ultimate  fate;  under  classical  laws  they  seemed  to  be 
heading  towards  an  intolerable  situation — the  star  could 
not  stop  losing  heat,  but  it  would  have  insufficient  energy 
to  be  able  to  cool  down!* 

Transition  to  a  New  Theory.  By  1925  the  machinery 
of  current  theory  had  developed  another  flaw  and  was 
urgently  calling  for  reconstruction;  Bohr's  model  of  the 
atom  had  quite  definitely  broken  down.  This  is  the 
model,  now  very  familiar,  which  pictures  the  atom  as 
a  kind  of  solar  system  with  a  central  positively  charged 
nucleus  and  a  number  of  elecrons  describing  orbits  about 
it  like  planets,  the  important  feature  being  that  the 
possible  orbits  are  limited  by  the  rules  referred  to  on 
p.  190.  Since  each  line  in  the  spectrum  of  the  atom  is 
emitted  by  the  jump  of  an  electron  between  two  par- 

*  The  energy  is  required  because  on  cooling  down  the  matter  must 
regain  a  more  normal  density  and  this  involves  a  great  expansion  of 
volume  of  the  star.  In  the  expansion  work  has  to  be  done  against  the 
force  of  gravity. 


TRANSITION  TO  A  NEW  THEORY  205 

ticular  orbits,  the  classification  of  the  spectral  lines  must 
run  parallel  with  the  classification  of  the  orbits  by  their 
quantum  numbers  in  the  model.  When  the  spectro- 
scopists  started  to  unravel  the  various  series  of  lines  in 
the  spectra  they  found  it  possible  to  assign  an  orbit 
jump  for  every  line — they  could  say  what  each  line 
meant  in  terms  of  the  model.  But  now  questions  of 
finer  detail  have  arisen  for  which  this  correspondence 
ceases  to  hold.  One  must  not  expect  too  much  from  a 
model,  and  it  would  have  been  no  surprise  if  the  model 
had  failed  to  exhibit  minor  phenomena  or  if  its  accuracy 
had  proved  imperfect.  But  the  kind  of  trouble  now 
arising  was  that  only  two  orbit  jumps  were  provided 
in  the  model  to  represent  three  obviously  associated 
spectral  lines;  and  so  on.  The  model  which  had  been 
so  helpful  in  the  interpretation  of  spectra  up  to  a  point, 
suddenly  became  altogether  misleading;  and  spectro- 
scopists  were  forced  to  turn  away  from  the  model  and 
complete  their  classification  of  lines  in  a  way  which 
ignored  it.  They  continued  to  speak  of  orbits  and 
orbit  jumps  but  there  was  no  longer  a  complete  one- 
to-one  correspondence  with  the  orbits  shown  in  the 
model.* 

The  time  was  evidently  ripe  for  the  birth  of  a  new 
theory.  The  situation  then  prevailing  may  be  summar- 
ised  as   follows : 

(1)  The  general  working  rule  was  to  employ  the 
classical  laws  with  the  supplementary  proviso  that 
whenever  anything  of   the  nature   of   action   appears   it 

*Each  orbit  or  state  of  the  atom  requires  three  (or,  for  later  refine- 
ments, four)  quantum  numbers  to  define  it.  The  first  two  quantum 
numbers  are  correctly  represented  in  the  Bohr  model ;  but  the  third 
number  which  discriminates  the  different  lines  forming  a  doublet  or 
multiplet  spectrum  is  represented  wrongly — a  much  more  serious  failure 
than  if  it  were  not  represented  at  all. 


206      THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

must  be  made  equal  to  h)  or  sometimes  to  an  integral  mul- 
tiple of  h. 

(2)  The  proviso  often  led  to  a  self-contradictory  use 
of  the  classical  theory.  Thus  in  the  Bohr  atom  the 
acceleration  of  the  electron  in  its  orbit  would  be  gov- 
erned by  classical  electrodynamics  whilst  its  radiation 
would  be  governed  by  the  h  rule.  But  in  classical  elec- 
trodynamics the  acceleration  and  the  radiation  are  indis- 
solubly  connected. 

(3)  The  proper  sphere  of  classical  laws  was  known. 
They  are  a  form  taken  by  the  more  general  laws  in  a 
limiting  case,  viz.  when  the  number  of  quanta  concerned 
is  very  large.  Progress  in  the  investigation  of  the  com- 
plete system  of  more  general  laws  must  not  be  ham- 
pered by  classical  conceptions  which  contemplate  only  the 
limiting  case. 

(4)  The  present  compromise  involved  the  recognition 
that  light  has  both  corpuscular  and  wave  properties. 
The  same  idea  seems  to  have  been  successfully  extended 
to  matter  and  confirmed  by  experiment.  But  this  success 
only  renders  the  more  urgent  some  less  contradictory 
way  of  conceiving  these  properties. 

(5)  Although  the  above  working  rule  had  generally 
been  successful  in  its  predictions,  it  was  found  to  give 
a  distribution  of  electron  orbits  in  the  atom  differing  in 
some  essential  respects  from  that  deduced  spectroscopi- 
cally.  Thus  a  reconstruction  was  required  not  only  to 
remove  logical  objections  but  to  meet  the  urgent  de- 
mands of  practical  physics. 

Development  of  the  New  Quantum  Theory.  The  "New 
Quantum  Theory"  originated  in  a  remarkable  paper 
by  Heisenberg  in  the  autumn  of  1925.  I  am  writing 
the  first  draft  of  this  lecture  just  twelve  months  after 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  NEW  THEORY  207 

the  appearance  of  the  paper.  That  does  not  give  long 
for  development;  nevertheless  the  theory  has  already 
gone  through  three  distinct  phases  associated  with  the 
names  of  Born  and  Jordan,  Dirac,  Schrodinger.  My 
chief  anxiety  at  the  moment  is  lest  another  phase  of 
reinterpretation  should  be  reached  before  the  lecture 
can  be  delivered.  In  an  ordinary  way  we  should  describe 
the  three  phases  as  three  distinct  theories.  The  pioneer 
work  of  Heisenberg  governs  the  whole,  but  the  three 
theories  show  wide  differences  of  thought.  The  first 
entered  on  'the  new  road  in  a  rather  matter-of-fact 
way;  the  second  was  highly  transcendental,  almost 
mystical;  the  third  seemed  at  first  to  contain  a  reac- 
tion towards  classical  ideas,  but  that  was  probably  a 
false  impression.  You  will  realise  the  anarchy  of 
this  branch  of  physics  when  three  successive  pre- 
tenders seize  the  throne  in  twelve  months;  but  you 
will  not  realise  the  steady  progress  made  in  that  time 
unless  you  turn  to  the  mathematics  of  the  subject. 
As  regards  philosophical  ideas  the  three  theories  are 
poles  apart;  as  regards  mathematical  content  they  are 
one  and  the  same.  Unfortunately  the  mathematical 
content  is  just  what  I  am  forbidden  to  treat  of  in  these 
lectures. 

I  am,  however,  going  to  transgress  to  the  extent  of 
writing  down  one  mathematical  formula  for  you  to  con- 
template; I  shall  not  be  so  unreasonable  as  to  expect 
you  to  understand  it.  All  authorities  seem  to  be  agreed 
that  at,  or  nearly  at,  the  root  of  everything  in  the  phy- 
sical world  lies  the  mystic  formula 

qp—pq  =  ih/2Tz 

We  do  not  yet  understand  that;  probably  if  we  could 
understand  it  we   should  not  think  it  so   fundamental. 


208      THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

Where  the  trained  mathematician  has  the  advantage  is 
that  he  can  use  it,  and  in  the  past  year  or  two  it  has 
been  used  in  physics  with  very  great  advantage  indeed. 
It  leads  not  only  to  those  phenomena  described  by  the 
older  quantum  laws  such  as  the  h  rule,  but  to  many 
related  phenomena  which  the  older  formulation  could 
not  treat. 

On  the  right-hand  side,  besides  h  (the  atom  of  action) 
and  the  merely  numerical  factor  2tt,  there  appears  i  (the 
square  root  of  — i)  which  may  seem  rather  mystical. 
But  this  is  only  a  well-known  subterfuge;  and  far  back 
in  the  last  century  physicists  and  engineers  were  well 
aware  that  V  —  i  in  their  formulae  was  a  kind  of  sig- 
nal to  look  out  for  waves  or  oscillations.  The  right- 
hand  side  contains  nothing  unusual,  but  the  left-hand  side 
baffles  imagination.  We  call  q  and  p  co-ordinates  and  mo- 
menta, borrowing  our  vocabulary  from  the  world  of 
space  and  time  and  other  coarse-grained  experience; 
but  that  gives  no  real  light  on  their  nature,  nor  does 
it  explain  why  qp  is  so  ill-behaved  as  to  be  unequal 
to  pq. 

It  is  here  that  the  three  theories  differ  most  essen- 
tially. Obviously  q  and  p  cannot  represent  simple 
numerical  measures,  for  then  qp — pq  would  be  zero. 
For  Schrodinger  p  is  an  operator.  His  "momentum" 
is  not  a  quantity  but  a  signal  to  us  to  perform  a  certain 
mathematical  operation  on  any  quantities  which  may 
follow.  For  Born  and  Jordan  p  is  a  matrix — not  one 
quantity,  nor  several  quantities,  but  an  infinite  number 
of  quantities  arranged  in  systematic  array.  For  Dirac 
p  is  a  symbol  without  any  kind  of  numerical  interpreta- 
tion; he  calls  it  a  ^-number,  which  is  a  way  of  saying 
that  it  is  not  a  number  at  all. 

I   venture  to  think  that  there  is   an  idea   implied  in 


DEVELOPMENT  OF  NEW  THEORY  209 

Dirac^s  treatment  which  may  have  great  philosophical 
significance,  independently  of  any  question  of  success  in 
this  particular  application.  The  idea  is  that  in  digging 
deeper  and  deeper  into  that  which  lies  at  the  base  of 
physical  phenomena  we  must  be  prepared  to  come  to 
entities  which,  like  many  things  in  our  conscious  experi- 
ence, are  not  measurable  by  numbers  in  any  way;  and 
further  it  suggests  how  exact  science,  that  is  to  say  the 
science  of  phenomena  correlated  to  measure-numbers, 
can  be  founded  on  such  a  basis. 

One  of  the  greatest  changes  in  physics  between  the 
nineteenth  century  and  the  present  day  has  been  the 
change  in  our  ideal  of  scientific  explanation.  It  was  the 
boast  of  the  Victorian  physicist  that  he  would  not  claim 
to  understand  a  thing  until  he  could  make  a  model  of 
it;  and  by  a  model  he  meant  something  constructed  of 
levers,  geared  wheels,  squirts,  or  other  appliances 
familiar  to  an  engineer.  Nature  in  building  the  universe 
was  supposed  to  be  dependent  on  just  the  same  kind  of 
resources  as  any  human  mechanic;  and  when  the  physi- 
cist sought  an  explanation  of  phenomena  his  ear  was 
straining  to  catch  the  hum  of  machinery.  The  man  who 
could  make  gravitation  out  of  cog-wheels  would  have 
been  a  hero  in  the  Victorian  age. 

Nowadays  we  do  not  encourage  the  engineer  to  build 
the  world  for  us  out  of  his  material,  but  we  turn  to  the 
mathematician  to  build  it  out  of  his  material.  Doubtless 
the  mathematician  is  a  loftier  being  than  the  engineer, 
but  perhaps  even  he  ought  not  to  be  entrusted  with  the 
Creation  unreservedly.  We  are  dealing  in  physics  with 
a  symbolic  world,  and  we  can  scarcely  avoid  employing 
the  mathematician  who  is  the  professional  wielder  of 
symbols;  but  he  must  rise  to  the  full  opportunities  of  the 
responsible  task  entrusted  to  him  and  not  indulge   too 


210      THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

freely  his  own  bias  for  symbols  with  an  arithmetical 
interpretation.  If  we  are  to  discern  controlling  laws  of 
Nature  not  dictated  by  the  mind  it  would  seem  neces- 
sary to  escape  as  far  as  possible  from  the  cut-and-dried 
framework  into  which  the  mind  is  so  ready  to  force 
everything  that  it  experiences. 

I  think  that  in  principle  Dirac's  method  asserts  this 
kind  of  emancipation.  He  starts  with  basal  entities 
inexpressible  by  numbers  or  number-systems  and  his 
basal  laws  are  symbolic  expressions  unconnected  with 
arithmetical  operations.  The  fascinating  point  is  that 
as  the  development  proceeds  actual  numbers  are  exuded 
from  the  symbols.  Thus  although  p  and  q  individually 
have  no  arithmetical  interpretation,  the  combination 
qp — pq  has  the  arithmetical  interpretation  expressed  by 
the  formula  above  quoted.  By  furnishing  numbers, 
though  itself  non-numerical,  such  a  theory  can  well  be 
the  basis  for  the  measure-numbers  studied  in  exact 
science.  The  measure-numbers,  which  are  all  that  we 
glean  from  a  physical  survey  of  the  world,  cannot  be 
the  whole  world;  they  may  not  even  be  so  much  of  it 
as  to  constitute  a  self-governing  unit.  This  seems  the 
natural  interpretation  of  Dirac's  procedure  in  seeking 
the  governing  laws  of  exact  science  in  a  non-arithmetical 
calculus. 

I  am  afraid  it  is  a  long  shot  to  predict  anything  like 
this  emerging  from  Dirac's  beginning;  and  for  the 
moment  Schrodinger  has  rent  much  of  the  mystery  from 
the  />'s  and  qs  by  showing  that  a  less  transcendental 
interpretation  is  adequate  for  present  applications.  But 
I  like  to  think  that  we  may  have  not  yet  heard  the  last 
of  the  idea. 

Schrodinger's  theory  is  now  enjoying  the  full  tide 
of  popularity,  partly  because  of  intrinsic  merit,  but  also, 


OUTLINE  OF  SCHRODINGER'S  THEORY      211 

I  suspect,  partly  because  it  is  the  only  one  of  the  three 
that  is  simple  enough  to  be  misunderstood.  Rather 
against  my  better  judgment  I  will  try  to  give  a  rough 
impression  of  the  theory.  It  would  probably  be  wiser 
to  nail  up  over  the  door  of  the  new  quantum  theory  a 
notice,  "Structural  alterations  in  progress — No  admit- 
tance except  on  business",  and  particularly  to  warn  the 
doorkeeper  to  keep  out  prying  philosophers.  I  will, 
however,  content  myself  with  the  protest  that,  whilst 
Schrodinger's  theory  is  guiding  us  to  sound  and  rapid 
progress  in  many  of  the  mathematical  problems  con- 
fronting us  and  is  indispensable  in  its  practical  utility, 
I  do  not  see  the  least  likelihood  that  his  ideas  will  sur- 
vive long  in  their  present  form. 

Outline  of  Schrodinger's  Theory.  Imagine  a  sub-aether 
whose  surface  is  covered  with  ripples.  The  oscillations 
of  the  ripples  are  a  million  times  faster  than  those  of 
visible  light — too  fast  to  come  within  the  scope  of  our 
gross  experience.  Individual  ripples  are  beyond  our 
ken;  what  we  can  appreciate  is  a  combined  effect — when 
by  convergence  and  coalescence  the  waves  conspire  to 
create  a  disturbed  area  of  extent  large  compared  with 
individual  ripples  but  small  from  our  own  Brobding- 
nagian  point  of  view.  Such  a  disturbed  area  is  recog- 
nised as  a  material  particle;  in  particular  it  can  be  an 
electron. 

The  sub-aether  is  a  dispersive  medium,  that  is  to  say 
the  ripples  do  not  all  travel  with  the  same  velocity;  like 
water-ripples  their  speed  depends  on  their  wave-length 
or  period.  Those  of  shorter  period  travel  faster.  More- 
over the  speed  may  be  modified  by  local  conditions. 
This  modification  is  the  counterpart  in  Schrodinger's 
theory  of  a  field  of  force  in  classical  physics.     It  will 


212      THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

readily  be  understood  that  if  we  are  to  reduce  all  phe- 
nomena to  a  propagation  of  waves,  then  the  influence 
of  a  body  on  phenomena  in  its  neighbourhood  (com- 
monly described  as  the  field  of  force  caused  by  its 
presence)  must  consist  in  a  modification  of  the  propa- 
gation of  waves  in  the  region  surrounding  it. 

We  have  to  connect  these  phenomena  in  the  sub- 
aether  with  phenomena  in  the  plane  of  our  gross  ex- 
perience. As  already  stated,  a  local  stormy  region  is 
detected  by  us  as  a  particle;  to  this  we  now  add  that  the 
frequency  (number  of  oscillations  per  second)  of  the 
waves  constituting  the  disturbance  is  recognised  by  us 
as  the  energy  of  the  particle.  We  shall  presently  try  to 
explain  how  the  period  manages  to  manifest  itself  to  us 
in  this  curiously  camouflaged  way;  but  however  it  comes 
about,  the  recognition  of  a  frequency  in  the  sub-aether 
as  an  energy  in  gross  experience  gives  at  once  the  con- 
stant relation  between  period  and  energy  which  we  have 
called  the  h  rule. 

Generally  the  oscillations  in  the  sub-aether  are  too 
rapid  for  us  to  detect  directly;  their  frequency  reaches 
the  plane  of  ordinary  experience  by  affecting  the  speed 
of  propagation,  because  the  speed  depends  (as  already 
stated)  on  the  wave-length  or  frequency.  Calling  the 
frequency  v,  the  equation  expressing  the  law  of  propa- 
gation of  the  ripples  will  contain  a  term  in  v.  There  will 
be  another  term  expressing  the  modification  caused  by 
the  "field  of  force"  emanating  from  the  bodies  present 
in  the  neighbourhood.  This  can  be  treated  as  a  kind  of 
spurious  v,  since  it  emerges  into  our  gross  experience 
by  the  same  method  that  v  does.  If  v  produces  those 
phenomena  which  make  us  recognise  it  as  energy,  the 
spurious  v  will  produce  similar  phenomena  correspond- 
ing to  a  spurious  kind  of  energy.     Clearly  the  latter  will 


OUTLINE  OF  SCHRODINGER'S  THEORY      213 

be  what  we  call  potential  energy,  since  it  originates  from 
influences  attributable  to  the  presence  of  surrounding 
objects. 

Assuming  that  we  know  both  the  real  v  and  the 
spurious  or  potential  v  for  our  ripples,  the  equation  of 
wave-propagation  is  settled,  and  we  can  proceed  to  solve 
any  problem  concerning  wave-propagation.  In  particular 
we  can  solve  the  problem  as  to  how  the  stormy  areas 
move  about.  This  gives  a  remarkable  result  which 
provides  the  first  check  on  our  theory.  The  stormy 
areas  (if  small  enough)  move  under  precisely  the  same 
laws  that  govern  the  motions  of  particles  in  classical 
mechanics.  The  equations  for  the  motion  of  a  wave- 
group  with  given  frequency  and  potential  frequency  are 
the  same  as  the  classical  equations  of  motion  of  a  par- 
ticle with  the  corresponding  energy  and  potential  energy. 

It  has  to  be  noticed  that  the  velocity  of  a  stormy  area 
or  group  of  waves  is  not  the  same  as  the  velocity  of  an 
individual  wave.  This  is  well  known  in  the  study  of 
water-waves  as  the  distinction  between  group-velocity 
and  wave-velocity.  It  is  the  group-velocity  that  is  ob- 
served by  us  as  the  motion  of  the  material  particle. 

We  should  have  gained  very  little  if  our  theory  did 
no  more  than  re-establish  the  results  of  classical  me- 
chanics on  this  rather  fantastic  basis.  Its  distinctive 
merits  begin  to  be  apparent  when  we  deal  with  pheno- 
mena not  covered  by  classical  mechanics.  We  have 
considered  a  stormy  area  of  so  small  extent  that  its 
position  is  as  definite  as  that  of  a  classical  particle,  but 
we  may  also  consider  an  area  of  wider  extent.  No 
precise  delimitation  can  be  drawn  between  a  large  area 
and  a  small  area,  so  that  we  shall  continue  to  associate 
the  idea  of  a  particle  with  it;  but  whereas  a  small 
concentrated    storm    fixes    the    position    of    the    particle 


214      THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

closely,  a  more  extended  storm  leaves  it  very  vague.  If 
we  try  to  interpret  an  extended  wave-group  in  classical 
language  we  say  that  it  is  a  particle  which  is  not  at  any 
definite  point  of  space,  but  is  loosely  associated  with  a 
wide  region. 

Perhaps  you  may  think  that  an  extended  stormy  area 
ought  to  represent  diffused  matter  in  contrast  to  a  con- 
centrated particle.  That  is  not  Schrodinger's  theory. 
The  spreading  is  not  a  spreading  of  density;  it  is  an 
indeterminacy  of  position,  or  a  wider  distribution  of  the 
probability  that  the  particle  lies  within  particular  limits 
of  position.  Thus  if  we  come  across  Schrodinger  waves 
uniformly  filling  a  vessel,  the  interpretation  is  not  that 
the  vessel  is  filled  with  matter  of  uniform  density,  but 
that  it  contains  one  particle  which  is  equally  likely  to  be 
anywhere. 

The  first  great  success  of  this  theory  was  in  repre- 
senting the  emission  of  light  from  a  hydrogen  atom — 
a  problem  far  outside  the  scope  of  classical  theory.  The 
hydrogen  atom  consists  of  a  proton  and  electron  which 
must  be  translated  into  their  counterparts  in  the  sub- 
aether.  We  are  not  interested  in  what  the  proton  is 
doing,  so  we  do  not  trouble  about  its  representation  by 
waves;  what  we  want  from  it  is  its  field  of  force,  that  is 
to  say,  the  spurious  v  which  it  provides  in  the  equation 
of  wave-propagation  for  the  electron.  The  waves 
travelling  in  accordance  with  this  equation  constitute 
Schrodinger's  equivalent  for  the  electron;  and  any  solu- 
tion of  the  equation  will  correspond  to  some  possible 
state  of  the  hydrogen  atom.  Now  it  turns  out  that 
(paying  attention  to  the  obvious  physical  limitation  that 
the  waves  must  not  anywhere  be  of  infinite  amplitude) 
solutions  of  this  wave-equation  only  exist  for  waves  with 
particular   frequencies.     Thus   in  a  hydrogen  atom  the 


OUTLINE  OF  SCHRODINGER'S  THEORY      215 

sub-aethereal  waves  are  limited  to  a  particular  discrete 
series  of  frequencies.  Remembering  that  a  frequency 
in  the  sub-aether  means  an  energy  in  gross  experience, 
the  atom  will  accordingly  have  a  discrete  series  of  pos- 
sible energies.  It  is  found  that  this  series  of  energies 
is  precisely  the  same  as  that  assigned  by  Bohr  from  his 
rules  of  quantisation  (p.  191).  It  is  a  considerable 
advance  to  have  determined  Jiese  energies  by  a  wave- 
theory  instead  of  by  an  inexplicable  mathematical  rule. 
Further,  when  applied  to  more  complex  atoms  Schro- 
dinger's  theory  succeeds  on  those  points  where  the  Bohr 
model  breaks  down;  it  always  gives  the  right  number  of 
energies  or  "orbits"  to  provide  one  orbit  jump  for  each 
observed  spectral  line. 

It  is,  however,  an  advantage  not  to  pass  from  wave- 
frequency  to  classical  energy  at  this  stage,  but  to  follow 
the  course  of  events  in  the  sub-aether  a  little  farther. 
It  would  be  difficult  to  think  of  the  electron  as  having 
two  energies  (i.e.  being  in  two  Bohr  orbits)  simultane- 
ously; but  there  is  nothing  to  prevent  waves  of  two  dif- 
ferent frequencies  being  simultaneously  present  in  the 
sub-aether.  Thus  the  wave-theory  allows  us  easily  to 
picture  a  condition  which  the  classical  theory  could  only 
describe  in  paradoxical  terms.  Suppose  that  two  sets 
of  waves  are  present.  If  the  difference  of  frequency  is 
not  very  great  the  two  systems  of  waves  will  produce 
"beats".  If  two  broadcasting  stations  are  transmitting 
on  wave-lengths  near  together  we  hear  a  musical  note 
or  shriek  resulting  from  the  beats  of  the  two  carrier 
waves;  the  individual  oscillations  are  too  rapid  to  affect 
the  ear,  but  they  combine  to  give  beats  which  are  slow 
enough  to  affect  the  ear.  In  the  same  way  the  individual 
wave-systems  in  the  sub-aether  are  composed  of  oscilla- 
tions too  rapid  to  affect  our  gross  senses ;  but  their  beats 


216      THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

are  sometimes  slow  enough  to  come  within  the  octave 
covered  by  the  eye.  These  beats  are  the  source  of  the 
light  coming  from  the  hydrogen  atom,  and  mathematical 
calculation  shows  that  their  frequencies  are  precisely 
those  of  the  observed  light  from  hydrogen.  Hetero- 
dyning of  the  radio  carrier  waves  produces  sound; 
heterodyning  of  the  sub-aethereal  waves  produces  light. 
Not  only  does  this  theory  give  the  periods  of  the  dif- 
ferent lines  in  the  spectra,  but  it  also  predicts  their  in- 
tensities— a  problem  which  the  older  quantum  theory  had 
no  means  of  tackling.  It  should,  however,  be  under- 
stood that  the  beats  are  not  themselves  to  be  identified 
with  light-waves;  they  are  in  the  sub-aether,  whereas 
light-waves  are  in  the  aether.  They  provide  the  oscil- 
lating source  which  in  some  way  not  yet  traced  sends  out 
light-waves  of  its  own  period. 

What  precisely  is  the  entity  which  we  suppose  to  be 
oscillating  when  we  speak  of  the  waves  in  the  sub- 
aether?  It  is  denoted  by  op,  and  properly  speaking  we 
should  regard  it  as  an  elementary  indefinable  of  the 
wave-theory.  But  can  we  give  it  a  classical  interpreta- 
tion of  any  kind?  It  seems  possible  to  interpret  it  as  a 
probability.  The  probability  of  the  particle  or  electron 
being  within  a  given  region  is  proportional  to  the  amount 
of  ip  in  that  region.  So  that  if  ip  is  mainly  concentrated 
in  one  small  stormy  area,  it  is  practically  certain  that 
the  electron  is  there;  we  are  then  able  to  localise  it 
definitely  and  conceive  of  it  as  a  classical  particle.  But 
the  ip-waves  of  the  hydrogen  atom  are  spread  about 
all  over  the  atom;  and  there  is  no  definite  localisation  of 
the  electron,  though  some  places  are  more  probable  than 
others.* 

*  The  probability  is  often  stated  to  be  proportional  to  ty2,  instead  of 
\p,  as  assumed  above.     The  whole  interpretation  is  very  obscure,  but  it 


OUTLINE  OF  SCHRODINGER'S  THEORY      217 

Attention  must  be  called  to  one  highly  important 
consequence  of  this  theory.  A  small  enough  stormy 
area  corresponds  very  nearly  to  a  particle  moving  about 
under  the  classical  laws  of  motion;  it  would  seem  there- 
fore that  a  particle  definitely  localised  as  a  moving  point 
is  stricdy  the  limit  when  the  stormy  area  is  reduced  to 
a  point.  But  curiously  enough  by  continually  reducing 
the  area  of  the  storm  we  never  quite  reach  the  ideal 
classical  particle;  we  approach  it  and  then  recede  from 
it  again.  We  have  seen  that  the  wave-group  moves  like 
a  particle  (localised  somewhere  within  the  area  of  the 
storm)  having  an  energy  corresponding  to  the  frequency 
of  the  waves;  therefore  to  imitate  a  particle  exactly,  not 
only  must  the  area  be  reduced  to  a  point  but  the  group 
must  consist  of  waves  of  only  one  frequency.  The  two 
conditions  are  irreconcilable.  With  one  frequency  we 
can  only  have  an  infinite  succession  of  waves  not  ter- 
minated by  any  boundary.  A  boundary  to  the  group  is 
provided  by  interference  of  waves  of  slightly  different 
length,  so  that  while  reinforcing  one  another  at  the 
centre  they  cancel  one  another  at  the  boundary.  Roughly 
speaking,  if  the  group  has  a  diameter  of  1000  wave- 
lengths there  must  be  a  range  of  wave-length  of  o-i  per 
cent.,  so  that  1000  of  the  longest  waves  and  1001  of 
the  shortest  occupy  the  same  distance.  If  we  take  a 
more   concentrated  stormy   area   of   diameter    10  wave- 

seems  to  depend  on  whether  you  are  considering  the  probability  after 
you  know  what  has  happened  or  the  probability  for  the  purposes  of 
prediction.  The  ijj2  is  obtained  by  introducing  two  symmetrical  systems 
of  ij>-waves  travelling  in  opposite  directions  in  time;  one  of  these  must 
presumably  correspond  to  probable  inference  from  what  is  known  (or 
is  stated)  to  have  been  the  condition  at  a  later  time.  Probability  neces- 
sarily means  "probability  in  the  light  of  certain  given  information",  so 
that  the  probability  cannot  possibly  be  represented  by  the  same  function 
in  different  classes  of  problems  with  different  initial  data. 


2i 8      THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

lengths  the  range  is  increased  to  10  per  cent.;  10  of 
the  longest  and  1 1  of  the  shortest  waves  must  extend  the 
same  distance.  In  seeking  to  make  the  position  of  the 
particle  more  definite  by  reducing  the  area  we  make  its 
energy  more  vague  by  dispersing  the  frequencies  of  the 
waves.  So  our  particle  can  never  have  simultaneously 
a  perfectly  definite  position  and  a  perfectly  definite 
energy;  it  always  has  a  vagueness  of  one  kind  or  the 
other  unbefitting  a  classical  particle.  Hence  in  delicate 
experiments  we  must  not  under  any  circumstances  expect 
to  find  particles  behaving  exactly  as  a  classical  particle 
was  supposed  to  do — a  conclusion  which  seems  to  be  in 
accordance  with  the  modern  experiments  on  diffraction 
of  electrons  already  mentioned. 

We  remarked  that  Schrodinger's  picture  of  the  hy- 
drogen atom  enabled  it  to  possess  something  that  would 
be  impossible  on  Bohr's  theory,  viz.  two  energies  at 
once.  For  a  particle  or  electron  this  is  not  merely  per- 
missive, but  compulsory — otherwise  we  can  put  no  limits 
to  the  region  where  it  may  be.  You  are  not  asked  to 
imagine  the  state  of  a  particle  with  several  energies; 
what  is  meant  is  that  our  current  picture  of  an  electron 
as  a  particle  with  single  energy  has  broken  down,  and 
we  must  dive  below  into  the  sub-aether  if  we  wish  to 
follow  the  course  of  events.  The  picture  of  a  particle 
may,  however,  be  retained  when  we  are  not  seeking  high 
accuracy;  if  we  do  not  need  to  know  the  energy  more 
closely  than  I  per  cent.,  a  series  of  energies  ranging 
over  i  per  cent,  can  be  treated  as  one  definite  energy. 

Hitherto  I  have  only  considered  the  waves  correspond- 
ing to  one  electron;  now  suppose  that  we  have  a  prob- 
lem involving  two  electrons.  How  shall  they  be  repre- 
sented? "Surely,  that  is  simple  enough!  We  have  only 
to  take  two  stormy  areas  instead  of  one."     I  am  afraid 


OUTLINE  OF  SCHRODINGER'S  THEORY      219 

not.  Two  stormy  areas  would  correspond  to  a  single 
electron  uncertain  as  to  which  area  it  was  located  in. 
So  long  as  there  is  the  faintest  probability  of  the  first 
electron  being  in  any  region,  we  cannot  make  the  Schro- 
dinger  waves  there  represent  a  probability  belonging  to 
a  second  electron.  Each  electron  wants  the  whole  of 
three-dimensional  space  for  its  waves;  so  Schrodinger 
generously  allows  three  dimensions  for  each  of  them. 
For  two  electrons  he  requires  a  six-dimensional  sub- 
aether.  He  then  successfully  applies  his  method  on  the 
same  lines  as  before.  I  think  you  will  see  now  that 
Schrodinger  has  given  us  what  seemed  to  be  a  com- 
prehensible physical  picture  only  to  snatch  it  away  again. 
His  sub-aether  does  not  exist  in  physical  space;  it  is  in 
a  "configuration  space"  imagined  by  the  mathematician 
for  the  purpose  of  solving  his  problems,  and  imagined 
afresh  with  different  numbers  of  dimensions  according 
to  the  problem  proposed.  It  was  only  an  accident 
that  in  the  earliest  problems  considered  the  configu- 
ration space  had  a  close  correspondence  with  physical 
space,  suggesting  some  degree  of  objective  reality 
of  the  waves.  Schrodinger's  wave-mechanics  is  not 
a  physical  theory  but  a  dodge — and  a  very  good  dodge 
too. 

The  fact  is  that  the  almost  universal  applicability  of 
this  wave-mechanics  spoils  all  chance  of  our  taking  it 
seriously  as  a  physical  theory.  A  delightful  illustration 
of  this  occurs  incidentally  in  the  work  of  Dirac.  In  one 
of  the  problems,  which  he  solves  by  Schrodinger  waves, 
the  frequency  of  the  waves  represents  the  number  of 
systems  of  a  given  kind.  The  wave-equation  is  formu- 
lated and  solved,  and  (just  as  in  the  problem  of  the 
hydrogen  atom)  it  is  found  that  solutions  only  exist  for 
a  series  of  special  values  of  the  frequency.     Consequently 


220      THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

the  number  of  systems  of  the  kind  considered  must 
have  one  of  a  discrete  series  of  values.  In  Dirac's 
problem  the  series  turns  out  to  be  the  series  of  integers. 
Accordingly  we  infer  that  the  number  of  systems  must 
be  either  i,  2,  3,  4,  .  .  .,  but  can  never  be  2%  f°r 
example.  It  is  satisfactory  that  the  theory  should  give 
a  result  so  well  in  accordance  with  our  experience ! 
But  we  are  not  likely  to  be  persuaded  that  the  true 
explanation  of  why  we  count  in  integers  is  afforded  by  a 
system  of  waves. 

Principle  of  Indeterminacy.  My  apprehension  lest  a 
fourth  version  of  the  new  quantum  theory  should 
appear  before  the  lectures  were  delivered  was  not  ful- 
filled; but  a  few  months  later  the  theory  definitely 
entered  on  a  new  phase.  It  was  Heisenberg  again  who 
set  in  motion  the  new  development  in  the  summer  of 
1927,  and  the  consequences  were  further  elucidated  by 
Bohr.  The  outcome  of  it  is  a  fundamental  general 
principle  which  seems  to  rank  in  importance  with  the 
principle  of  relativity.  I  shall  here  call  it  the  "principle 
of  indeterminacy". 

The  gist  of  it  can  be  stated  as  follows :  a  particle  may 
have  position  or  it  may  have  velocity  but  it  cannot  in  any 
exact  sense  have  both. 

If  we  are  content  with  a  certain  margin  of  inaccuracy 
and  if  we  are  content  with  statements  that  claim  no 
certainty  but  only  high  probability,  then  it  is  possible 
to  ascribe  both  position  and  velocity  to  a  particle.  But 
if  we  strive  after  a  more  accurate  specification  of  position 
a  very  remarkable  thing  happens;  the  greater  accuracy 
can  be  attained,  but  it  is  compensated  by  a  greater 
inaccuracy  in  the  specification  of  the  velocity.  Similarly 
if  the  specification  of  the  velocity  is  made  more  accurate 
the  position  becomes  less  determinate. 


PRINCIPLE  OF  INDETERMINACY  221 

Suppose  for  example  that  we  wish  to  know  the  posi- 
tion and  velocity  of  an  electron  at  a  given  moment. 
Theoretically  it  would  be  possible  to  fix  the  position  with 
a  probable  error  of  about  1/1000  of  a  millimetre  and 
the  velocity  with  a  probable  error  of  1  kilometre  per 
second.  But  an  error  of  1/1000  of  a  millimetre  is  large 
compared  with  that  of  some  of  our  space  measurements; 
is  there  no  conceivable  way  of  fixing  the  position  to 
1/10,000  of  a  millimetre?  Certainly;  but  in  that  case  it 
will  only  be  possible  to  fix  the  velocity  with  an  error  of 
10  kilometres  per  second. 

The  conditions  of  our  exploration  of  the  secrets  of 
Nature  are  such  that  the  more  we  bring  to  light  the 
secret  of  position  the  more  the  secret  of  velocity  is 
hidden.  They  are  like  the  old  man  and  woman  in  the 
weather-glass;  as  one  comes  out  of  one  door,  the  other 
retires  behind  the  other  door.  When  we  encounter  un- 
expected obstacles  in  finding  out  something  which  we 
wish  to  know,  there  are  two  possible  courses  to  take.  It 
may  be  that  the  right  course  is  to  treat  the  obstacle 
as  a  spur  to  further  efforts;  but  there  is  a  second 
possibility — that  we  have  been  trying  to  find  some- 
thing which  does  not  exist.  You  will  remember  that 
that  was  how  the  relativity  theory  accounted  for  the 
apparent  concealment  of  our  velocity  through  the 
aether. 

When  the  concealment  is  found  to  be  perfectly  sys- 
tematic, then  we  must  banish  the  corresponding  entity 
from  the  physical  world.  There  is  really  no  option. 
The  link  with  our  consciousness  is  completely  broken. 
When  we  cannot  point  to  any  causal  effect  on  anything 
that  comes  into  our  experience,  the  entity  merely  becomes 
part  of  the  unknown — undifferentiated  from  the  rest  of 
the  vast  unknown.  From  time  to  time  physical  discover- 
ies are  made;  and  new  entities,  coming  out  of  the  un- 


222      THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

known,  become  connected  to  our  experience  and  are  duly 
named.  But  to  leave  a  lot  of  unattached  labels  floating 
in  the  as  yet  undifferentiated  unknown  in  the  hope  that 
they  may  come  in  useful  later  on,  is  no  particular  sign 
of  prescience  and  is  not  helpful  to  science.  From  this 
point  of  view  we  assert  that  the  description  of  the  posi- 
tion and  velocity  of  an  electron  beyond  a  limited  num- 
ber of  places  of  decimals  is  an  attempt  to  describe  some- 
thing that  does  not  exist;  although  curiously  enough  the 
description  of  position  or  of  velocity  if  it  had  stood  alone 
might  have  been  allowable. 

Ever  since  Einstein's  theory  showed  the  importance 
of  securing  that  the  physical  quantities  which  we  talk 
about  are  actually  connected  to  our  experience,  we  have 
been  on  our  guard  to  some  extent  against  meaningless 
terms.  Thus  distance  is  defined  by  certain  operations  of 
measurement  and  not  with  reference  to  nonsensical  con- 
ceptions such  as  the  "amount  of  emptiness"  between 
two  points.  The  minute  distances  referred  to  in  atomic 
physics  naturally  aroused  some  suspicion,  since  it  is  not 
always  easy  to  say  how  the  postulated  measurements 
could  be  imagined  to  be  carried  out.  I  would  not  like 
to  assert  that  this  point  has  been  cleared  up;  but  at  any 
rate  it  did  not  seem  possible  to  make  a  clean  sweep  of 
all  minute  distances,  because  cases  could  be  cited  in  which 
there  seemed  no  natural  limit  to  the  accuracy  of  deter- 
mination of  position.  Similarly  there  are  ways  of 
determining  momentum  apparently  unlimited  in  accuracy. 
What  escaped  notice  was  that  the  two  measurements 
interfere  with  one  another  in  a  systematic  way,  so  that 
the  combination  of  position  with  momentum,  legitimate 
on  the  large  scale,  becomes  indefinable  on  the  small 
scale.  The  principle  of  indeterminacy  is  scientifically 
stated  as  follows:  if  q  is  a  co-ordinate  and  p  the  corre- 


PRINCIPLE  OF  INDETERMINACY  223 

sponding  momentum,  the  necessary  uncertainty  of  our 
knowledge  of  q  multiplied  by  the  uncertainty  of  p  is  of 
the  order  of  magnitude  of  the  quantum  constant  h. 

A  general  kind  of  reason  for  this  can  be  seen  without 
much  difficulty.  Suppose  it  is  a  question  of  knowing 
the  position  and  momentum  of  an  electron.  So  long  as 
the  electron  is  not  interacting  with  the  rest  of  the  uni- 
verse we  cannot  be  aware  of  it.  We  must  take  our 
chance  of  obtaining  knowledge  of  it  at  moments  when  it 
is  interacting  with  something  and  thereby  producing 
effects  that  can  be  observed.  But  in  any  such  interaction 
a  complete  quantum  is  involved;  and  the  passage  of  this 
quantum,  altering  to  an  important  extent  the  conditions 
at  the  moment  of  our  observation,  makes  the  information 
out  of  date  even  as  we  obtain  it. 

Suppose  that  (ideally)  an  electron  is  observed  under 
a  powerful  microscope  in  order  to  determine  its  position 
with  great  accuracy.  For  it  to  be  seen  at  all  it  must  be 
illuminated  and  scatter  light  to  reach  the  eye.  The  least 
it  can  scatter  is  one  quantum.  In  scattering  this  it  re- 
ceives from  the  light  a  kick  of  unpredictable  amount; 
we  can  only  state  the  respective  probabilities  of  kicks 
of  different  amounts.  Thus  the  condition  of  our  ascer- 
taining the  position  is  that  we  disturb  the  electron  in  an 
incalculable  way  which  will  prevent  our  subsequently  as- 
certaining how  much  momentum  it  had.  However,  we 
shall  be  able  to  ascertain  the  momentum  with  an  uncer- 
tainty represented  by  the  kick,  and  if  the  probable  kick 
is  small  the  probable  error  will  be  small.  To  keep  the 
kick  small  we  must  use  a  quantum  of  smali  energy,  that 
is  to  say,  light  of  long  wave-length.  But  to  use  long 
wave-length  reduces  the  accuracy  of  our  microscope. 
The  longer  the  waves,  the  larger  the  diffraction  images. 
And  it  must  be  remembered  that  it  takes  a  great  many 


224      THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

quanta  to  outline  the  diffraction  image;  our  one  scattered 
quantum  can  only  stimulate  one  atom  in  the  retina  of 
the  eye,  at  some  haphazard  point  within  the  theoretical 
diffraction  image.  Thus  there  will  be  an  uncertainty  in 
our  determination  of  position  of  the  electron  propor- 
tional to  the  size  of  the  diffraction  image.  We  are  in  a 
dilemma.  We  can  improve  the  determination  of  the 
position  with  the  microscope  by  using  light  of  shorter 
wave-length,  but  that  gives  the  electron  a  greater  kick 
and  spoils  the  subsequent  determination  of  momentum. 

A  picturesque  illustration  of  the  same  dilemma  is 
afforded  if  we  imagine  ourselves  trying  to  see  one  of  the 
electrons  in  an  atom.  For  such  finicking  work  it  is  no 
use  employing  ordinary  light  to  see  with;  it  is  far  too 
gross,  its  wave-length  being  greater  than  the  whole 
atom.  We  must  use  fine-grained  illumination  and  train 
our  eyes  to  see  with  radiation  of  short  wave-length — 
with  X-rays  in  fact.  It  is  well  to  remember  that  X-rays 
have  a  rather  disastrous  effect  on  atoms,  so  we  had  better 
use  them  sparingly.  The  least  amount  we  can  use  is  one 
quantum.  Now,  if  we  are  ready,  will  you  watch,  whilst 
I  flash  one  quantum  of  X-rays  on  to  the  atom?  I  may 
not  hit  the  electron  the  first  time;  in  that  case,  of  course, 
you  will  not  see  it.  Try  again;  this  time  my  quantum 
has  hit  the  electron.  Look  sharp,  and  notice  where  it  is. 
Isn't  it  there?  Bother!  I  must  have  blown  the  electron 
out  of  the  atom. 

This  is  not  a  casual  difficulty;  it  is  a  cunningly 
arranged  plot — a  plot  to  prevent  you  from  seeing 
something  that  does  not  exist,  viz.  the  locality  of  the 
electron  within  the  atom.  If  I  use  longer  waves  which 
do  no  harm,  they  will  not  define  the  electron  sharply 
enough  for  you  to  see  where  it  is.  In  shortening  the  wave- 
length, just  as  the  light  becomes  fine  enough  its  quan- 


A  NEW  EPISTEMOLOGY  225 

turn  becomes  too  rough  and  knocks  the  electron  out  of 
the  atom. 

Other  examples  of  the  reciprocal  uncertainty  have 
been  given,  and  there  seems  to  be  no  doubt  that  it  is 
entirely  general.  The  suggestion  is  that  an  association 
of  exact  position  with  exact  momentum  can  never  be 
discovered  by  us  because  there  is  no  such  thing  in  Nature. 
This  is  not  inconceivable.  Schrodinger's  model  of  the 
particle  as  a  wave-group  gives  a  good  illustration  of  how 
it  can  happen.  We  have  seen  (p.  217)  that  as  the  posi- 
tion of  a  wave-group  becomes  more  defined  the  energy 
(frequency)  becomes  more  indeterminate,  and  vice  versa. 
I  think  that  that  is  the  essential  value  of  Schrodinger's 
theory;  it  refrains  from  attributing  to  a  particle  a  kind 
of  determinacy  which  does  not  correspond  to  anything 
in  Nature.  But  I  would  not  regard  the  principle  of 
indeterminacy  as  a  result  to  be  deduced  from  Schro- 
dinger's theory;  it  is  the  other  way  about.  The  principle 
of  indeterminacy,  like  the  principle  of  relativity,  repre- 
sents the  abandonment  of  a  mistaken  assumption  which 
we  never  had  sufficient  reason  for  making.  Just  as  we 
were  misled  into  untenable  ideas  of  the  aether  through 
trusting  to  an  analogy  with  the  material  ocean,  so  we 
have  been  misled  into  untenable  ideas  of  the  attributes 
of  the  microscopic  elements  of  world-structure  through 
trusting  to  analogy  with  gross  particles. 

A  New  Epistemology.  The  principle  of  indeterminacy 
is  epistemological.  It  reminds  us  once  again  that  the 
world  of  physics  is  a  world  contemplated  from  within 
surveyed  by  appliances  which  are  part  of  it  and  subject 
to  its  laws.  What  the  world  might  be  deemed  like  if 
probed  in  some  supernatural  manner  by  appliances  not 
furnished  by  itself  we  do  not  profess  to  know. 


226      THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

There  is  a  doctrine  well  known  to  philosophers  that 
the  moon  ceases  to  exist  when  no  one  is  looking  at  it. 
I  will  not  discuss  the  doctrine  since  I  have  not  the  least 
idea  what  is  the  meaning  of  the  word  existence  when 
used  in  this  connection.  At  any  rate  the  science  of  as- 
tronomy has  not  been  based  on  this  spasmodic  kind  of 
moon.  In  the  scientific  world  (which  has  to  fulfil  func- 
tions less  vague  than  merely  existing)  there  is  a  moon 
which  appeared  on  the  scene  before  the  astronomer;  it 
reflects  sunlight  when  no  one  sees  it;  it  has  mass  when 
no  one  is  measuring  the  mass;  it  is  distant  240,000  miles 
from  the  earth  when  no  one  is  surveying  the  distance; 
and  it  will  eclipse  the  sun  in  1999  even  if  the  human  race 
has  succeeding  in  killing  itself  off  before  that  date.  The 
moon — the  scientific  moon — has  to  play  the  part  of  a 
continuous  causal  element  in  a  world  conceived  to  be  all 
causally  interlocked. 

What  should  we  regard  as  a  complete  description  of 
this  scientific  world?  We  must  not  introduce  anything 
like  velocity  through  aether,  which  is  meaningless  since 
it  is  not  assigned  any  causal  connection  with  our  ex- 
perience. On  the  other  hand  we  cannot  limit  the  de- 
scription to  the  immediate  data  of  our  own  spasmodic 
observations.  The  description  should  include  nothing 
that  is  unobservable  but  a  great  deal  that  is  actually 
unobserved.  Virtually  we  postulate  an  infinite  army  of 
watchers  and  measurers.  From  moment  to  moment  they 
survey  everything  that  can  be  surveyed  and  measure 
everything  that  can  be  measured  by  methods  which  we 
ourselves  might  conceivably  employ.  Everything  they 
measure  goes  down  as  part  of  the  complete  description 
of  the  scientific  world.  We  can,  of  course,  introduce 
derivative  descriptions,  words  expressing  mathematical 
combinations  of  the  immediate  measures  which  may  give 


A  NEW  EPISTEMOLOGY  227 

greater  point  to  the  description — so  that  we  may  not 
miss  seeing  the  wood  for  the  trees. 

By  employing  the  known  physical  laws  expressing 
the  uniformities  of  Nature  we  can  to  a  large  extent 
dispense  with  this  army  of  watchers.  We  can  afford  to 
let  the  moon  out  of  sight  for  an  hour  or  two  and  deduce 
where  it  has  been  in  the  meantime.  But  when  I  assert 
that  the  moon  (which  I  last  saw  in  the  west  an  hour  ago) 
is  now  setting,  I  assert  this  not  as  my  deduction  but  as 
a  true  fact  of  the  scientific  world.  I  am  still  postulating 
the  imaginary  watcher;  I  do  not  consult  him,  but  I 
retain  him  to  corroborate  my  statement  if  it  is  chal- 
lenged. Similarly,  when  we  say  that  the  distance  of 
Sirius  is  50  billion  miles  we  are  not  giving  a  merely  con- 
ventional interpretation  to  its  measured  parallax;  we  in- 
tend to  give  it  the  same  status  in  knowledge  as  if  some- 
one had  actually  gone  through  the  operation  of  laying 
measuring  rods  end  to  end  and  counted  how  many  were 
needed  to  reach  to  Sirius;  and  we  should  listen  patiently 
to  anyone  who  produced  reasons  for  thinking  that  our 
deductions  did  not  correspond  to  the  "real  facts",  i.e. 
the  facts  as  known  to  our  army  of  measurers.  If  we 
happen  to  make  a  deduction  which  could  not  conceivably 
be  corroborated  or  disproved  by  these  diligent  measur- 
ers, there  is  no  criterion  of  its  truth  or  falsehood  and  it 
is  thereby  a  meaningless  deduction. 

This  theory  of  knowledge  is  primarily  intended  to 
apply  to  our  macroscopic  or  large-scale  survey  of  the 
physical  world,  but  it  has  usually  been  taken  for  granted 
that  it  is  equally  applicable  to  a  microscopic  study.  We 
have  at  last  realised  the  disconcerting  fact  that  though 
it  applies  to  the  moon  it  does  not  apply  to  the 
electron. 

It  does  not  hurt  the  moon  to  look  at  it.     There  is  no 


228      THE  NEW  QUANTUM  THEORY 

inconsistency  in  supposing  it  to  have  been  under  the 
surveillance  of  relays  of  watchers  whilst  we  were  asleep. 
But  it  is  otherwise  with  an  electron.  At  certain  times, 
viz.  when  it  is  interacting  with  a  quantum,  it  might  be 
detected  by  one  of  our  watchers;  but  between  whiles  it 
virtually  disappears  from  the  physical  world,  having  no 
interaction  with  it.  We  might  arm  our  observers  with 
flash-lamps  to  keep  a  more  continuous  watch  on  its 
doings;  but  the  trouble  is  that  under  the  flashlight  it 
will  not  go  on  doing  what  it  was  doing  in  the  dark. 
There  is  a  fundamental  inconsistency  in  conceiving  the 
microscopic  structure  of  the  physical  world  to  be  under 
continuous  survey  because  the  surveillance  would  itself 
wreck  the  whole  machine. 

I  expect  that  at  first  this  will  sound  to  you  like  a 
merely  dialectical  difficulty.  But  there  is  much  more  in 
it  than  that.  The  deliberate  frustration  of  our  efforts  to 
bring  knowledge  of  the  microscopic  world  into  orderly 
plan,  is  a  strong  hint  to  alter  the  plan. 

It  means  that  we  have  been  aiming  at  a  false  ideal  of 
a  complete  description  of  the  world.  There  has  not  yet 
been  time  to  make  serious  search  for  a  new  epistemology 
adapted  to  these  conditions.  It  has  become  doubtful 
whether  it  will  ever  be  possible  to  construct  a  physical 
world  solely  out  of  the  knowable — the  guiding  principle 
in  our  macroscopic  theories.  If  it  is  possible,  it  involves 
a  great  upheaval  of  the  present  foundations.  It  seems 
more  likely  that  we  must  be  content  to  admit  a  mixture 
of  the  knowable  and  unknowable.  This  means  a  denial 
of  determinism,  because  the  data  required  for  a  pre- 
diction of  the  future  will  include  the  unknowable  ele- 
ments of  the  past.  I  think  it  was  Heisenberg  who  said, 
uThe  question  whether  from  a  complete  knowledge  of 
the  past  we  can  predict  the  future,  does  not  arise  because 


A  NEW  EPISTEMOLOGY  229 

a  complete  knowledge  of  the  past  involves   a   self-con- 
tradiction." 

It  is  only  through  a  quantum  action  that  the  outside 
world  can  interact  with  ourselves  and  knowledge  of  it 
can  reach  our  minds.  A  quantum  action  may  be  the 
means  of  revealing  to  us  some  fact  about  Nature,  but 
simultaneously  a  fresh  unknown  is  implanted  in  the  womb 
of  Time.  An  addition  to  knowledge  is  won  at  the  ex- 
pense of  an  addition  to  ignorance.  It  is  hard  to  empty 
the  well  of  Truth  with  a  leaky  bucket. 


Chapter  XI 

WORLD  BUILDING 

We  have  an  intricate  task  before  us.  We  are  going  to 
build  a  World — a  physical  world  which  will  give  a 
shadow  performance  of  the  drama  enacted  in  the  world 
of  experience.  We  are  not  very  expert  builders  as  yet; 
and  you  must  not  expect  the  performance  to  go  off 
without  a  hitch  or  to  have  the  richness  of  detail  which  a 
critical  audience  might  require.  But  the  method  about 
to  be  described  seems  to  give  the  bold  outlines;  doubt- 
less we  have  yet  to  learn  other  secrets  of  the  craft  of 
world  building  before  we  can  complete  the  design. 

The  first  problem  is  the  building  material.  I  remem- 
ber that  as  an  impecunious  schoolboy  I  used  to  read 
attractive  articles  on  how  to  construct  wonderful  con- 
trivances out  of  mere  odds  and  ends.  Unfortunately 
these  generally  included  the  works  of  an  old  clock,  a 
few  superfluous  telephones,  the  quicksilver  from  a 
broken  barometer,  and  other  oddments  which  happened 
not  to  be  forthcoming  in  my  lumber  room.  I  will  try 
not  to  let  you  down  like  that.  I  cannot  make  the  world 
out  of  nothing,  but  I  will  demand  as  little  specialised 
material  as  possible.  Success  in  the  game  of  World 
Building  consists  in  the  greatness  of  the  contrast 
between  the  specialised  properties  of  the  completed 
structure  and  the  unspecialised  nature  of  the  basal 
material. 

Relation  Structure.  We  take  as  building  material  rela- 
tions and  relata.  The  relations  unite  the  relata;  the 
relata  are  the  meeting  points  of  the  relations.     The  one 

230 


RELATION  STRUCTURE  231 

is  unthinkable  apart  from  the  other.  I  do  not  think  that 
a  more  general  starting-point  of  structure  could  be 
conceived. 

To  distinguish  the  relata  from  one  another  we  assign 
to  them  monomarks.  The  monomark  consists  of  four 
numbers  ultimately  to  be  called  "co-ordinates".  But 
co-ordinates  suggest  space  and  geometry  and  as  yet  there 
is  no  such  thing  in  our  scheme;  hence  for  the  present 
we  shall  regard  the  four  identification  numbers  as  no 
more  than  an  arbitrary  monomark.  Why  four  numbers? 
We  use  four  because  it  turns  out  that  ultimately  the 
structure  can  be  brought  into  better  order  that  way; 
but  we  do  not  know  why  this  should  be  so.  We  have 
got  so  far  as  to  understand  that  if  the  relations  insisted 
on  a  threefold  or  a  fivefold  ordering  it  would  be  much 
more  difficult  to  build  anything  interesting  out  of  them; 
but  that  is  perhaps  an  insufficient  excuse  for  the 
special  assumption  of  fourfold  order  in  the  primitive 
material. 

The  relation  between  two  human  individuals  in  its 
broadest  sense  comprises  every  kind  of  connection  or 
comparison  between  them — consanguinity,  business  trans- 
actions, comparative  stature,  skill  at  golf — any  kind  of 
description  in  which  both  are  involved.  For  generality 
we  shall  suppose  that  the  relations  in  our  world-material 
are  likewise  composite  and  in  no  way  expressible  in  nu- 
merical measure.  Nevertheless  there  must  be  some  kind 
of  comparability  or  likeness  of  relations,  as  there  is  in 
the  relations  of  human  individuals;  otherwise  there 
would  be  nothing  more  to  be  said  about  the  world  than 
that  everything  in  it  was  utterly  unlike  everything  else. 
To  put  it  another  way,  we  must  postulate  not  only  rela- 
tions between  the  relata  but  some  kind  of  relation  of 
likeness  between  some   of  the  relations.     The  slightest 


232  WORLD  BUILDING 

concession  in  this  direction  will  enable  us  to  link  the 
whole  into  a  structure. 

We  assume  then  that,  considering  a  relation  between 
two  relata,  it  will  in  general  be  possible  to  pick  out  two 
other  relata  close  at  hand  which  stand  to  one  another 
in  a  "like"  relation.  By  "like"  I  do  not  mean  "like  in 
every  respect",  but  like  in  respect  to  one  of  the  aspects 
of  the  composite  relation.  How  is  the  particular  aspect 
selected?  If  our  relata  were  human  individuals  different 
judgments  of  likeness  would  be  made  by  the  geneal- 
ogist, the  economist,  the  psychologist,  the  sportsman, 
etc.;  and  the  building  of  structure  would  here  diverge 
along  a  number  of  different  lines.  Each  could  build  his 
own  world-structure  from  the  common  basal  material 
of  humanity.  There  is  no  reason  to  deny  that  a  similar 
diversity  of  worlds  could  be  built  out  of  our  postulated 
material.  But  all  except  one  of  these  worlds  will  be 
stillborn.  Our  labour  will  be  thrown  away  unless  the 
world  we  have  built  is  the  one  which  the  mind  chooses 
to  vivify  into  a  world  of  experience.  The  only  definition 
we  can  give  of  the  aspect  of  the  relations  chosen  for  the 
criterion  of  likeness,  is  that  it  is  the  aspect  which  will 
ultimately  be  concerned  in  the  getting  into  touch  of  mind 
wTith  the  physical  world.  But  that  is  beyond  the  province 
of  physics. 

This  one-to-one  correspondence  of  "likeness"  is  only 
supposed  to  be  definite  in  the  limit  when  the  relations 
are  very  close  together  in  the  structure.  Thus  we  avoid 
any  kind  of  comparison  at  a  distance  which  is  as 
objectionable  as  action  at  a  distance.  Let  me  confess  at 
once  that  I  do  not  know  what  I  mean  here  by  "very 
close  together".  As  yet  space  and  time  have  not  been 
built.  Perhaps  we  might  say  that  only  a  few  of  the 
relata  possess  relations  whose  comparability  to  the  first 


RELATION  STRUCTURE 


233 


is  definite,  and  take  the  definiteness  of  the  comparability 
as  the  criterion  of  contiguity.  I  hardly  know.  The 
building  at  this  point  shows  some  cracks,  but  I  think  it 
should  not  be  beyond  the  resources  of  the  mathematical 
logician  to  cement  them  up.  We  should  also  arrange  at 
this  stage  that  the  monomarks  are  so  assigned  as  to  give 
an  indication  of  contiguity. 


Fig.  7 

Let  us  start  with  a  relatum  A  and  a  relation  AP 
radiating  from  it.  Now  step  to  a  contiguous  relatum 
B  and  pick  out  the  "like"  relation  BQ.  Go  on  to 
another  contiguous  relatum  C  and  pick  out  the  relation 
CR  which  is  like  BQ.  (Note  that  since  C  is  farther 
from  A  than  from  B}  the  relation  at  C  which  is  like 
AP  is  not  so  definite  as  the  relation  which  is  like  BQ.) 
Step  by  step  we  may  make  the  comparison  round  a 
route  AEFA  which  returns  to  the  starting-point.  There 
is  nothing  to   ensure   that  the  final  relation  AP'  which 


234  WORLD  BUILDING 

has,  so  to  speak,  been  carried  round  the  circuit  will  be 
the   relation  AP  with  which  we  originally  started. 

We  have  now  two  relations  AP,  AP'  radiating  from 
the  first  relatum,  their  difference  being  connected  with 
a  certain  circuit  in  the  world  AEFA.  The  loose  ends  of 
the  relations  P  and  P  have  their  monomarks,  and  we 
can  take  the  difference  of  the  monomarks  (i.e.  the 
difference  of  the  identification  numbers  comprised  in 
them)  as  the  code  expression  for  the  change  introduced 
by  carrying  AP  round  the  circuit.  As  we  vary  the  circuit 
and  the  original  relation,  so  the  change  PP'  varies;  and 
the  next  step  is  to  find  a  mathematical  formula  express- 
ing this  dependence.  There  are  virtually  four  things  to 
connect,  the  circuit  counting  double  since,  for  example, 
a  rectangular  circuit  would  be  described  by  specifying 
two  sides.  Each  of  them  has  to  be  specified  by  four 
identification  numbers  (either  monomarks  or  derived 
from  monomarks) ;  consequently,  to  allow  for  all  com- 
binations, the  required  mathematical  formula  contains 
44  or  256  numerical  coefficients.  These  coefficients  give 
a  numerical  measure  of  the  structure  surrounding  the 
initial  relatum. 

This  completes  the  first  part  of  our  task  to  introduce 
numerical  measure  of  structure  into  the  basal  material. 
The  method  is  not  so  artificial  as  it  appears  at  first  sight. 
Unless  we  shirk  the  problem  by  putting  the  desired 
physical  properties  of  the  world  directly  into  the  original 
relations  and  relata,  we  must  derive  them  from  the 
structural  interlocking  of  the  relations;  and  such 
interlocking  is  naturally  traced  by  following  circuits 
among  the  relations.  The  axiom  of  comparability  of 
contiguous  relations  only  discriminates  between  like 
and  unlike,  and  does  not  initially  afford  any  means 
of  classifying  various  decrees  and  kinds  of  unlikeness; 


RELATION  STRUCTURE  235 

but  we  have  found  a  means  of  specifying  the  kind 
of  unlikeness  of  AP  and  AP'  by  reference  to  a  circuit 
which  "transforms"  one  into  the  other.  Thus  we  have 
built  a  quantitative  study  of  diversity  on  a  definition  of 
similarity. 

The  numerical  measures  of  structure  will  be  dependent 
on,  and  vary  according  to,  the  arbitrary  code  of  mono- 
marks used  for  the  identification  of  relata.  This,  how- 
ever, renders  them  especially  suitable  for  building  the 
ordinary  quantities  of  physics.  When  the  monomarks 
become  co-ordinates  of  space  and  time  the  arbitrary 
choice  of  the  code  will  be  equivalent  to  the  arbitrary 
choice  of  a  frame  of  space  and  time;  and  it  is  in  accord- 
ance with  the  theory  of  relativity  that  the  measures  of 
structure  and  the  physical  quantities  to  be  built  from 
them  should  vary  with  the  frame  of  space  and  time. 
Physical  quantities  in  general  have  no  absolute  value, 
but  values  relative  to  chosen  frames  of  reference  or 
codes  of  monomarks. 

We  have  now  fashioned  our  bricks  from  the  primitive 
clay  and  the  next  job  is  to  build  with  them.  The  256 
measures  of  structure  varying  from  point  to  point  of 
the  world  are  somewhat  reduced  in  number  when  dupli- 
cates are  omitted;  but  even  so  they  include  a  great  deal 
of  useless  lumber  which  we  do  not  require  for  the 
building.  That  seems  to  have  worried  a  number  of  the 
most  eminent  physicists;  but  I  do  not  quite  see  why. 
Ultimately  it  is  the  mind  that  decides  what  is  lumber — 
which  part  of  our  building  will  shadow  the  things  of 
common  experience,  and  which  has  no  such  counterpart. 
It  is  no  part  of  our  function  as  purveyors  of  building 
material  to  anticipate  what  will  be  chosen  for  the 
palace  of  the  mind.  The  lumber  will  now  be  dropped  as 
irrelevant  in  the  further  operations,  but  I  do  not  agree 


236  WORLD  BUILDING 

with  those  who  think  it  a  blemish  on  the  theory  that 
the  lumber  should  ever  have  appeared  in  it. 

By  adding  together  certain  of  the  measures  of  struc- 
ture in  a  symmetrical  manner  and  by  ignoring  others 
we  reduce  the  really  important  measures  to  16.*  These 
can  be  divided  into  10  forming  a  symmetrical  scheme 
and  6  forming  an  antisymmetrical  scheme.  This  is  the 
great  point  of  bifurcation  of  the  world. 

Symmetrical  coefficients  (10).  Out  of  these  we  find  it 
possible  to  construct  Geometry  and  Mechanics.  They 
are  the  ten  potentials  of  Einstein  (g,J).  We  derive 
from  them  space,  time,  and  the  world-curvatures  re- 
presenting the  mechanical  properties  of  matter,  viz. 
momentum,  energy,  stress,  etc. 

Antisymmetrical  coefficients  (6).  Out  of  these  we  con- 
struct Electromagnetism.  They  are  the  three  com- 
ponents of  electric  intensity  and  three  components  of 
magnetic  force.  We  derive  electric  and  magnetic 
potential,  electric  charge  and  current,  light  and  other 
electric  waves. 

We  do  not  derive  the  laws  and  phenomena  of 
atomicity.  Our  building  operation  has  somehow  been 
too  coarse  to  furnish  the  microscopic  structure  of  the 
world,  so  that  atoms,  electrons  and  quanta  are  at  present 
beyond  our  skill. 

But  in  regard  to  what  is  called  field-physics  the 
construction  is  reasonably  complete.  The  metrical, 
gravitational  and  electromagnetic  fields  are  all  included. 
We  build  the  quantities  enumerated  above;  and  they 
obey  the  great  laws  of  field-physics  in  virtue  of  the  way 
in  which  they  have  been  built.  That  is  the  special  fea- 
ture; the  field  laws — conservation  of  energy,  mass,  mo- 

*  Mathematically  we  contract  the   original   tensor   of   the   fourth   rank 
to  one  of  the  second  rank. 


IDENTICAL  LAWS  237 

mentum  and  of  electric  charge,  the  law  of  gravitation, 
Maxwell's  equations — are  not  controlling  laws.*  They 
are  truisms.  Not  truisms  when  approached  in  the  way 
the  mind  looks  out  on  the  world,  but  truisms  when  we 
encounter  them  in  a  building  up  of  the  world  from  a 
basal  structure.  I  must  try  to  make  clear  our  new 
attitude  to  these  laws. 

Identical  Laws.  Energy  momentum  and  stress,  which 
we  have  identified  with  the  ten  principal  curvatures  of 
the  world,  are  the  subject  of  the  famous  laws  of  con- 
servation of  energy  and  momentum.  Granting  that  the 
identification  is  correct,  these  laws  are  mathematical 
identities.  Violation  of  them  is  unthinkable.  Perhaps 
I  can  best  indicate  their  nature  by  an  analogy. 

An  aged  college  Bursar  once  dwelt  secluded  in  his 
rooms  devoting  himself  entirely  to  accounts.  He  realised 
the  intellectual  and  other  activities  of  the  college  only 
as  they  presented  themselves  in  the  bills.  He  vaguely 
conjectured  an  objective  reality  at  the  back  of  it  all — 
some  sort  of  parallel  to  the  real  college — though  he 
could  only  picture  it  in  terms  of  the  pounds,  shillings 
and  pence  which  made  up  what  he  would  call  "the 
commonsense  college  of  everyday  experience".  The 
method  of  account-keeping  had  become  inveterate  habit 
handed  down  from  generations  of  hermit-like  bursars; 
he  accepted  the  form  of  accounts  as  being  part  of  the 
nature  of  things.  But  he  was  of  a  scientific  turn  and  he 
wanted  to  learn  more  about  the  college.  One  day  in 
looking  over  his  books  he  discovered  a  remarkable  law. 

*  One  law  commonly  grouped  with  these,  viz.  the  law  of  pondero- 
motive  force  of  the  electric  field,  is  not  included.  It  seems  to  be  impos- 
sible to  get  at  the  origin  of  this  law  without  tackling  electron  structure 
which  is  beyond  the  scope  of  our  present  exercise  in  world-building. 


238  WORLD  BUILDING 

For  every  item  on  the  credit  side  an  equal  item  appeared 
somewhere  else  on  the  debit  side.  "Ha  I"  said  the 
Bursar,  "I  have  discovered  one  of  the  great  laws  con- 
trolling the  college.  It  is  a  perfect  and  exact  law  of  the 
real  world.  Credit  must  be  called  plus  and  debit  minus; 
and  so  we  have  the  law  of  conservation  of  £  s.  d.  This 
is  the  true  way  to  find  out  things,  and  there  is  no  limit 
to  what  may  ultimately  be  discovered  by  this  scientific 
method.  I  will  pay  no  more  heed  to  the  superstitions 
held  by  some  of  the  Fellows  as  to  a  beneficent  spirit 
called  the  King  or  evil  spirits  called  the  University 
Commissioners.  I  have  only  to  go  on  in  this  way  and 
I  shall  succeed  in  understanding  why  prices  are  always 
going  up." 

I  have  no  quarrel  with  the  Bursar  for  believing  that 
scientific  investigation  of  the  accounts  is  a  road  to  exact 
(though  necessarily  partial)  knowledge  of  the  reality 
behind  them.  Things  may  be  discovered  by  this  method 
which  go  deeper  than  the  mere  truism  revealed  by  his 
first  effort.  In  any  case  his  life  is  especially  concerned 
with  accounts  and  it  is  proper  that  he  should  discover 
the  laws  of  accounts  whatever  their  nature.  But  I  would 
point  out  to  him  that  a  discovery  of  the  overlapping  of 
the  different  aspects  in  which  the  realities  of  the  college 
present  themselves  in  the  world  of  accounts,  is  not  a 
discovery  of  the  laws  controlling  the  college;  that  he 
has  not  even  begun  to  find  the  controlling  laws.  The 
college  may  totter  but  the  Bursar's  accounts  still  balance. 

The  law  of  conservation  of  momentum  and  energy 
results  from  the  overlapping  of  the  different  aspects  in 
which  the  "non-emptiness  of  space"  presents  itself  to 
our  practical  experience.  Once  again  we  find  that  a 
fundamental  law  of  physics  is  no  controlling  law  but  a 
"put-up  job"  as  soon  as  we  have  ascertained  the  nature 


SELECTIVE  INFLUENCE  OF  THE  MIND      239 

of  that  which  is  obeying  it.  We  can  measure  certain 
forms  of  energy  with  a  thermometer,  momentum  with 
a  ballistic  pendulum,  stress  with  a  manometer.  Com- 
monly we  picture  these  as  separate  physical  entities 
whose  behaviour  towards  each  other  is  controlled  by 
a  law.  But  now  the  theory  is  that  the  three  instruments 
measure  different  but  slightly  overlapping  aspects  of  a 
single  physical  condition,  and  a  law  connecting  their 
measurements  is  of  the  same  tautological  type  as  a  "law" 
connecting  measurements  with  a  metre-rule  and  a  foot- 
rule. 

I  have  said  that  violation  of  these  laws  of  conserva- 
tion is  unthinkable.  Have  we  then  found  physical  laws 
which  will  endure  for  all  time  unshaken  by  any  future 
revolution?  But  the  proviso  must  be  remembered, 
"granting  that  the  identification  [of  their  subject 
matter]  is  correct".  The  law  itself  will  endure  as  long 
as  two  and  two  make  four;  but  its  practical  importance 
depends  on  our  knowing  that  which  obeys  it.  We 
think  we  have  this  knowledge,  but  do  not  claim  in- 
fallibility in  this  respect.  From  a  practical  point  of  view 
the  law  would  be  upset,  if  it  turned  out  that  the  thing 
conserved  was  not  that  which  we  are  accustomed  to 
measure  with  the  above-mentioned  instruments  but 
something  slightly  different. 

Selective  Influence  of  the  Mind.  This  brings  us  very 
near  to  the  problem  of  bridging  the  gulf  between  the 
scientific  world  and  the  world  of  everyday  experience. 
The  simpler  elements  of  the  scientific  world  have  no 
immediate  counterparts  in  everyday  experience;  we 
use  them  to  build  things  which  have  counterparts. 
Energy,  momentum  and  stress  in  the  scientific  world 
shadow    well-known    features    of    the    familiar    world. 


240  WORLD  BUILDING 

I  feel  stress  in  my  muscles;  one  form  of  energy  gives  me 
the  sensation  of  warmth;  the  ratio  of  momentum  to  mass 
is  velocity,  which  generally  enters  into  my  experience 
as  change  of  position  of  objects.  When  I  say  that  I  feel 
these  things  I  must  not  forget  that  the  feeling,  in  so  far 
as  it  is  located  in  the  physical  world  at  all,  is  not  in  the 
things  themselves  but  in  a  certain  corner  of  my  brain. 
In  fact,  the  mind  has  also  invented  a  craft  of  world- 
building;  its  familiar  world  is  built  not  from  the  dis- 
tribution of  relata  and  relations  but  by  its  own  peculiar 
interpretation  of  the  code  messages  transmitted  along 
the  nerves  into  its  sanctum. 

Accordingly  we  must  not  lose  sight  of  the  fact  that 
the  world  which  physics  attempts  to  describe  arises 
from  the  convergence  of  two  schemes  of  world-building. 
If  we  look  at  it  only  from  the  physical  side  there  is 
inevitably  an  arbitrariness  about  the  building.  Given 
the  bricks — the  16  measures  of  world-structure — there 
are  all  sorts  of  things  we  might  build.  Or  we  might 
take  up  again  some  of  the  rejected  lumber  and  build  a 
still  wider  variety  of  things.  But  we  do  not  build 
arbitrarily;  we  build  to  order.  The  things  we  build  have 
certain  remarkable  properties;  they  have  these  pro- 
perties in  virtue  of  the  way  they  are  built,  but  they  also 
have  them  because  such  properties  were  ordered.  There 
is  a  general  description  which  covers  at  any  rate  most 
of  the  building  operations  needed  in  the  construction 
of  the  physical  world;  in  mathematical  language  the 
operation  consists  in  Hamiltonian  differentiation  of  an 
invariant  function  of  the  16  measures  of  structure.  I  do 
not  think  that  there  is  anything  in  the  basal  relation- 
structure  that  cries  out  for  this  special  kind  of  com- 
bination; the  significance  of  this  process  is  not  in 
inorganic  nature.     Its  significance  is  that  it  corresponds 


SELECTIVE  INFLUENCE  OF  THE  MIND      241 

to  an  outlook  adopted  by  the  mind  for  its  own  reasons; 
and  any  other  building  process  would  not  converge  to 
the  mental  scheme  of  world-building.  The  Hamiltonian 
derivative  has  just  that  kind  of  quality  which  makes  it 
stand  out  in  our  minds  as  an  active  agent  against  a 
passive  extension  of  space  and  time;  and  Hamiltonian 
differentiation  is  virtually  the  symbol  for  creation  of  an 
active  world  out  of  the  formless  background.  Not  once 
in  the  dim  past,  but  continuously  by  conscious  mind  is 
the  miracle  of  the  Creation  wrought. 

By  following  this  particular  plan  of  building  we 
construct  things  which  satisfy  the  law  of  conservation, 
that  is  to  say  things  which  are  permanent.  The  law  of 
conservation  is  a  truism  for  the  things  which  satisfy  it; 
but  its  prominence  in  the  scheme  of  law  of  the  physical 
world  is  due  to  the  mind  having  demanded  permanence. 
We  might  have  built  things  which  do  not  satisfy  this 
law.  In  fact  we  do  build  one  very  important  thing 
"action"  which  is  not  permanent;  in  respect  to  "action" 
physics  has  taken  the  bit  in  her  teeth,  and  has  insisted 
on  recognising  this  as  the  most  fundamental  thing  of  all, 
although  the  mind  has  not  thought  it  worthy  of  a  place 
in  the  familiar  world  and  has  not  vivified  it  by  any 
mental  image  or  conception.  You  will  understand  that 
the  building  to  which  I  refer  is  not  a  shifting  about  of 
material;  it  is  like  building  constellations  out  of  stars. 
The  things  which  we  might  have  built  but  did  not,  are 
there  just  as  much  as  those  we  did  build.  What  we  have 
called  building  is  rather  a  selection  from  the  patterns 
that  weave  themselves. 

The  element  of  permanence  in  the  physical  world, 
which  is  familiarly  represented  by  the  conception  of 
substance,  is  essentially  a  contribution  of  the  mind  to 
the   plan   of   building   or   selection.      We    can    see    this 


242  WORLD  BUILDING 

selective  tendency  at  work  in  a  comparatively  simple 
problem,  viz.  the  hydrodynamical  theory  of  the  ocean. 
At  first  sight  the  problem  of  what  happens  when  the 
water  is  given  some  initial  disturbance  depends  solely  on 
inorganic  laws;  nothing  could  be  more  remote  from  the 
intervention  of  conscious  mind.  In  a  sense  this  is  true; 
the  laws  of  matter  enable  us  to  work  out  the  motion 
and  progress  of  the  different  portions  of  the  water;  and 
there,  so  far  as  the  inorganic  world  is  concerned,  the 
problem  might  be  deemed  to  end.  But  actually  in 
hydrodynamical  textbooks  the  investigation  is  diverted 
in  a  different  direction,  viz.  to  the  study  of  the  motions 
of  waves  and  wave-groups.  The  progress  of  a  wave  is 
not  progress  of  any  material  mass  of  water,  but  of  a 
form  which  travels  over  the  surface  as  the  water  heaves 
up  and  down;  again  the  progress  of  a  wave-group  is  not 
the  progress  of  a  wave.  These  forms  have  a  certain 
degree  of  permanence  amid  the  shifting  particles  of 
water.  Anything  permanent  tends  to  become  dignified 
with  an  attribute  of  substantiality.  An  ocean  traveller 
has  even  more  vividly  the  impression  that  the  ocean  is 
made  of  waves  than  that  it  is  made  of  water.*  Ulti- 
mately it  is  this  innate  hunger  for  permanence  in  our 
minds  which  directs  the  course  of  development  of 
hydrodynamics,  and  likewise  directs  the  world-building 
out  of  the  sixteen  measures  of  structure. 

Perhaps  it  will  be  objected  that  other  things  besides 
mind  can  appreciate  a  permanent  entity  such  as  mass; 
a  weighing  machine  can  appreciate  it  and  move  a 
pointer  to  indicate  how  much  mass  there  is.  I  do  not 
think  that  is  a  valid  objection.  In  building  the  physical 
world  we  must  of  course  build  the  measuring  appliances 

*  This  was  not  intended   to   allude   to  certain  consequential   effects   of 
the  waves;  it  is  true,  I  think,  of  the  happier  impressions  of  the  voyage. 


SELECTIVE  INFLUENCE  OF  THE  MIND      243 

which  are  part  of  it;  and  the  measuring  appliances 
result  from  the  plan  of  building  in  the  same  way  as  the 
entities  which  they  measure.  If,  for  example,  we  had 
used  some  of  the  "lumber"  to  build  an  entity  x,  we 
could  presumably  construct  from  the  same  lumber  an 
appliance  for  measuring  x.  The  difference  is  this — if  the 
pointer  of  the  weighing  machine  is  reading  5  lbs.  a 
human  consciousness  is  in  a  mysterious  way  (not  yet 
completely  traced)  aware  of  the  fact,  whereas  if  the 
measuring  appliance  for  x  reads  5  units  no  human  mind 
is  aware  of  it.  Neither  x  nor  the  appliance  for  measur- 
ing x  have  any  interaction  with  consciousness.  Thus  the 
responsibility  for  the  fact  that  the  scheme  of  the  scientific 
world  includes  mass  but  excludes  x  rests  ultimately  with 
the  phenomena  of  consciousness. 

Perhaps  a  better  way  of  expressing  this  selective 
influence  of  mind  on  the  laws  of  Nature  is  to  say  that 
values  are  created  by  the  mind.  All  the  "light  and  shade" 
in  our  conception  of  the  world  of  physics  comes  in  this 
way  from  the  mind,  and  cannot  be  explained  without 
reference  to  the  characteristics  of  consciousness. 

The  world  which  we  have  built  from  the  relation- 
structure  is  no  doubt  doomed  to  be  pulled  about  a  good 
deal  as  our  knowledge  progresses.  The  quantum  theory 
shows  that  some  radical  change  is  impending.  But  I 
think  that  our  building  exercise  has  at  any  rate  widened 
our  minds  to  the  possibilities  and  has  given  us  a  different 
orientation  towards  the  idea  of  physical  law.  The  points 
which  I  stress  are: 

Firstly,  a  strictly  quantitative  science  can  arise  from 
a  basis  which  is  purely  qualitative.  The  comparability 
that  has  to  be  assumed  axiomatically  is  a  merely  quali- 
tative discrimination  of  likeness  and  unlikeness. 

Secondly,  the  laws  which  we  have  hitherto  regarded 


244  WORLD  BUILDING 

as  the  most  typical  natural  laws  are  of  the  nature  of 
truisms,  and  the  ultimate  controlling  laws  of  the  basal 
structure  (if  there  are  any)  are  likely  to  be  of  a  differ- 
ent type  from  any  yet  conceived. 

Thirdly,  the  mind  has  by  its  selective  power  fitted 
the  processes  of  Nature  into  a  frame  of  law  of  a  pattern 
largely  of  its  own  choosing;  and  in  the  discovery  of  this 
system  of  law  the  mind  may  be  regarded  as  regaining 
from  Nature  that  which  the  mind  has  put  into 
Nature. 

Three  Types  of  Law.  So  far  as  we  are  able  to  judge,  the 
laws  of  Nature  divide  themselves  into  three  classes: 
(i)  identical  laws,  (2)  statistical  laws,  (3)  transcenden- 
tal laws.  We  have  just  been  considering  the  identical 
laws,  i.e.  the  laws  obeyed  as  mathematical  identities  in 
virtue  of  the  way  in  which  the  quantities  obeying  them 
are  built.  They  cannot  be  regarded  as  genuine  laws  of 
control  of  the  basal  material  of  the  world.  Statistical 
laws  relate  to  the  behaviour  of  crowds,  and  depend  on 
the  fact  that  although  the  behaviour  of  each  individual 
may  be  extremely  uncertain  average  results  can  be 
predicted  with  confidence.  Much  of  the  apparent  uni- 
formity of  Nature  is  a  uniformity  of  averages.  Our 
gross  senses  only  take  cognisance  of  the  average  effect  of 
vast  numbers  of  individual  particles  and  processes;  and 
the  regularity  of  the  average  might  well  be  compatible 
with  a  great  degree  of  lawlessness  of  the  individual.  I  do 
not  think  it  is  possible  to  dismiss  statistical  laws  (such 
as  the  second  law  of  thermodynamics)  as  merely  mathe- 
matical adaptations  of  the  other  classes  of  law  to  certain 
practical  problems.  They  involve  a  peculiar  element 
of  their  own  connected  with  the  notion  of  a  priori  proba- 
bility; but  we  do  not  yet  seem  able  to  find  a  place  for 


THREE  TYPES  OF  LAW  245 

this  in  any  of  the  current  conceptions  of  the  world  sub- 
stratum. 

If  there  are  any  genuine  laws  of  control  of  the  physical 
world  they  must  be  sought  in  the  third  group — the 
transcendental  laws.  The  transcendental  laws  comprise 
all  those  which  have  not  become  obvious  identities  im- 
plied in  the  scheme  of  world-building.  They  are  con- 
cerned with  the  particular  behaviour  of  atoms,  electrons 
and  quanta — that  is  to  say,  the  laws  of  atomicity  of 
matter,  electricity  and  action.  We  seem  to  be  mak- 
ing some  progress  towards  formulating  them,  but  it  is 
clear  that  the  mind  is  having  a  much  harder  struggle  to 
gain  a  rational  conception  of  them  than  it  had  with  the 
classical  field-laws.  We  have  seen  that  the  field-laws, 
especially  the  laws  of  conservation,  are  indirecdy  imposed 
by  the  mind  which  has,  so  to  speak,  commanded  a  plan  of 
world-building  to  satisfy  them.  It  is  a  natural  suggestion 
that  the  greater  difficulty  in  elucidating  the  transcenden- 
tal laws  is  due  to  the  fact  that  we  are  no  longer  engaged 
in  recovering  from  Nature  what  we  have  ourselves  put 
into  Nature,  but  are  at  last  confronted  with  its  own  in- 
trinsic system  of  government.  But  I  scarcely  know  what 
to  think.  We  must  not  assume  that  the  possible  develop- 
ments of  the  new  attitude  towards  natural  law  have  been 
exhausted  in  a  few  short  years.  It  may  be  that  the  laws 
of  atomicity,  like  the  laws  of  conservation,  arise  only  in 
the  presentation  of  the  world  to  us  and  can  be  recognised 
as  identities  by  some  extension  of  the  argument  we  have 
followed.  But  it  is  perhaps  as  likely  that  after  we  have 
cleared  away  all  the  superadded  laws  which  arise  solely 
in  our  mode  of  apprehension  of  the  world  about  us,  there 
will  be  left  an  external  world  developing  under  genuine 
laws  of  control. 

At  present  we  can  notice  the  contrast  that  the  laws 


246  WORLD  BUILDING 

which  we  now  recognise  as  man-made  are  characterised 
by  continuity,  whereas  the  laws  to  which  the  mind  as 
yet  lays  no  claim  are  characterised  by  atomicity.  The 
quantum  theory  with  its  avoidance  of  fractions  and 
insistence  on  integral  units  seems  foreign  to  any  scheme 
which  we  should  be  likely  subconsciously  to  have  im- 
posed as  a  frame  for  natural  phenomena.  Perhaps  our 
final  conclusion  as  to  the  world  of  physics  will  resemble 
Kronecker's  view  of  pure  mathematics. 

uGod  made  the  integers,  all  else  is  the  work  of  man."* 

*  Die  ganzen  Zahlen  hat  Gott  gemacht;   alles   anderes  ist  Menschen- 
werk. 


Chapter  XII 
POINTER  READINGS 

Familiar  Conceptions  and  Scientific  Symbols.  We  have 
said  in  the  Introduction  that  the  raw  material  of  the 
scientific  world  is  not  borrowed  from  the  familiar  world. 
It  is  only  recently  that  the  physicist  has  deliberately  cut 
himself  adrift  from  familiar  conceptions.  He  did  not 
set  out  to  discover  a  new  world  but  to  tinker  with  the 
old.  Like  everyone  else  he  started  with  the  idea  that 
things  are  more  or  less  what  they  seem,  and  that  our 
vivid  impression  of  our  environment  may  be  taken  as 
a  basis  to  work  from.  Gradually  it  has  been  found  that 
some  of  its  most  obvious  features  must  be  rejected.  We 
learn  that  instead  of  standing  on  a  firm  immovable  earth 
proudly  rearing  our  heads  towards  the  vault  of  heaven, 
we  are  hanging  by  our  feet  from  a  globe  careering 
through  space  at  a  great  many  miles  a  second.  But  this 
new  knowledge  can  still  be  grasped  by  a  rearrangement 
of  familiar  conceptions.  I  can  picture  to  myself  quite 
vividly  the  state  of  affairs  just  described;  if  there  is  any 
strain,  it  is  on  my  credulity,  not  on  my  powers  of  con- 
ception. Other  advances  of  knowledge  can  be  accommo- 
dated by  that  very  useful  aid  to  comprehension — "like 
this  only  more  so".  For  example,  if  you  think  of  some- 
thing like  a  speck  of  dust  only  more  so  you  have  the 
atom  as  it  was  conceived  up  to  a  fairly  recent  date. 

In  addition  to  the  familiar  entities  the  physicist  had 
to  reckon  with  mysterious  agencies  such  as  gravitation 
or  electric  force;  but  this  did  not  disturb  his  general 
outlook.     We  cannot  say  what  electricity  is  "like"j  but 

247 


248  POINTER  READINGS 

at  first  its  aloofness  was  not  accepted  as  final.  It  was 
taken  to  be  one  of  the  main  aims  of  research  to  discover 
how  to  reduce  these  agencies  to  something  describable 
in  terms  of  familiar  conceptions — in  short  to  "explain" 
them.  For  example,  the  true  nature  of  electric  force 
might  be  some  kind  of  displacement  of  the  aether. 
(Aether  was  at  that  time  a  familiar  conception — like 
some  extreme  kind  of  matter  only  more  so.)  Thus 
there  grew  up  a  waiting-list  of  entities  which  should 
one  day  take  on  their  rightful  relation  to  conceptions 
of  the  familiar  world.  Meanwhile  physics  had  to 
treat  them  as  best  it  could  without  knowledge  of  their 
nature. 

It  managed  surprisingly  well.  Ignorance  of  the  nature 
of  these  entities  was  no  bar  to  successful  prediction  of 
behaviour.  We  gradually  awoke  to  the  fact  that  the 
scheme  of  treatment  of  quantities  on  the  waiting-list 
was  becoming  more  precise  and  more  satisfying  than 
our  knowledge  of  familiar  things.  Familiar  conceptions 
did  not  absorb  the  waiting-list,  but  the  waiting-list 
began  to  absorb  familiar  conceptions.  Aether,  after 
being  in  turn  an  elastic  solid,  a  jelly,  a  froth,  a  con- 
glomeration of  gyrostats,  was  denied  a  material  and 
substantial  nature  and  put  back  on  the  waiting-list.  It 
was  found  that  science  could  accomplish  so  much  with 
entities  whose  nature  was  left  in  suspense  that  it  began 
to  be  questioned  whether  there  was  any  advantage  in 
removing  the  suspense.  The  crisis  came  when  we  began 
to  construct  familiar  entities  such  as  matter  and  light 
out  of  things  on  the  waiting-list.  Then  at  last  it  was  seen 
that  the  linkage  to  familiar  concepts  should  be  through 
the  advanced  constructs  of  physics  and  not  at  the  be- 
ginning of  the  alphabet.  We  have  suffered,  and  we  still 
suffer,  from  expectations  that  electrons  and  quanta  must 


SCIENTIFIC  SYMBOLS  249 

be  in  some  fundamental  respects  like  materials  or  forces 
familiar  in  the  workshop — that  all  we  have  got  to  do  is 
to  imagine  the  usual  kind  of  thing  on  an  infinitely  smaller 
scale.  It  must  be  our  aim  to  avoid  such  prejudgments, 
which  are  surely  illogical;  and  since  we  must  cease  to 
employ  familiar  concepts,  symbols  have  become  the  only 
possible  alternative. 

The  synthetic  method  by  which  we  build  up  from 
its  own  symbolic  elements  a  world  which  will  imitate 
the  actual  behaviour  of  the  world  of  familiar  experience 
is  adopted  almost  universally  in  scientific  theories.  Any 
ordinary  theoretical  paper  in  the  scientific  journals 
tacitly  assumes  that  this  approach  is  adopted.  It  has 
proved  to  be  the  most  successful  procedure;  and  it  is  the 
actual  procedure  underlying  the  advances  set  forth  in 
the  scientific  part  of  this  book.  But  I  would  not  claim 
that  no  other  way  of  working  is  admissible.  We  agree 
that  at  the  end  of  the  synthesis  there  must  be  a  linkage 
to  the  familiar  world  of  consciousness,  and  we  are  not 
necessarily  opposed  to  attempts  to  reach  the  physical 
world  from  that  end.  From  the  point  of  view  of  philo- 
sophy it  is  desirable  that  this  entrance  should  be 
explored,  and  it  is  conceivable  that  it  may  be  fruitful 
scientifically.  If  I  have  rightly  understood  Dr.  White- 
head's philosophy,  that  is  the  course  which  he  takes.  It 
involves  a  certain  amount  of  working  backwards  (as 
we  should  ordinarily  describe  it) ;  but  his  method  of 
"extensive  abstraction"  is  intended  to  overcome  some 
of  the  difficulties  of  such  a  procedure.  I  am  not  qualified 
to  form  a  critical  judgment  of  this  work,  but  in  principle 
it  appears  highly  interesting.  Although  this  book  may 
in  most  respects  seem  diametrically  opposed  to  Dr. 
Whitehead's  widely  read  philosophy  of  Nature,  I  think 
it  would  be  truer  to  regard  him  as  an  ally  who  from  the 


250  POINTER  READINGS 

opposite  side  of  the  mountain  is  tunnelling  to  meet  his 
less  philosophically  minded  colleagues.  The  important 
thing  is  not  to  confuse  the  two  entrances. 

Nature  of  Exact  Science.  One  of  the  characteristics  of 
physics  is  that  it  is  an  exact  science,  and  I  have  generally 
identified  the  domain  of  physics  with  the  domain  of 
exact  science.  Strictly  speaking  the  two  are  not  synony- 
mous. We  can  imagine  a  science  arising  which  has  no 
contact  with  the  usual  phenomena  and  laws  of  physics, 
which  yet  admits  of  the  same  kind  of  exact  treatment. 
It  is  conceivable  that  the  Mendelian  theory  of  heredity 
may  grow  into  an  independent  science  of  this  kind,  for 
it  would  seem  to  occupy  in  biology  the  same  position 
that  the  atomic  theory  occupied  in  chemistry  a  hundred 
years  ago.  The  trend  of  the  theory  is  to  analyse  com- 
plex individuals  into  "unit  characters".  These  are  like 
indivisible  atoms  with  affinities  and  repulsions;  their 
matings  are  governed  by  the  same  laws  of  chance  which 
play  so  large  a  part  in  chemical  thermodynamics;  and 
numerical  statistics  of  the  characters  of  a  population  are 
predictable  in  the  same  way  as  the  results  of  a  chemical 
reaction. 

Now  the  effect  of  such  a  theory  on  our  philosophical 
views  of  the  significance  of  life  does  not  depend  on 
whether  the  Mendelian  atom  admits  of  a  strictly  physical 
explanation  or  not.  The  unit  character  may  be  contained 
in  some  configuration  of  the  physical  molecules  of  the 
carrier,  and  perhaps  even  literally  correspond  to  a  chem- 
ical compound;  or  it  may  be  something  superadded  which 
is  peculiar  to  living  matter  and  is  not  yet  comprised  in 
the  schedule  of  physical  entities.  That  is  a  side-issue. 
We  are  drawing  near  to  the  great  question  whether  there 
is  any  domain  of  activity — of  life,  of  consciousness,  of 


NATURE  OF  EXACT  SCIENCE  251 

deity — which  will  not  be  engulfed  by  the  advance  of 
exact  science;  and  our  apprehension  is  not  directed 
against  the  particular  entities  of  physics  but  against  all 
entities  of  the  category  to  which  exact  science  can  apply. 
For  exact  science  invokes,  or  has  seemed  to  invoke,  a 
type  of  law  inevitable  and  soulless  against  which  the 
human  spirit  rebels.  If  science  finally  declares  that  man 
is  no  more  than  a  fortuitous  concourse  of  atoms,  the 
blow  will  not  be  softened  by  the  explanation  that  the 
atoms  in  question  are  the  Mendelian  unit  characters 
and  not  the  material  atoms  of  the  chemist. 

Let  us  then  examine  the  kind  of  knowledge  which  is 
handled  by  exact  science.  If  we  search  the  examination 
papers  in  physics  and  natural  philosophy  for  the  more 
intelligible  questions  we  may  come  across  one  beginning 
something  like  this:  "An  elephant  slides  down  a 
grassy  hillside.  .  .  ."  The  experienced  candidate  knows 
that  he  need  not  pay  much  attention  to  this;  it  is  only 
put  in  to  give  an  impression  of  realism.  He  reads  on: 
"The  mass  of  the  elephant  is  two  tons."  Now  we  are 
getting  down  to  business;  the  elephant  fades  out  of  the 
problem  and  a  mass  of  two  tons  takes  its  place.  What 
exactly  is  this  two  tons,  the  real  subject-matter  of  the 
problem?  It  refers  to  some  property  or  condition  which 
we  vaguely  describe  as  "ponderosity"  occurring  in  a 
particular  region  of  the  external  world.  But  we  shall  not 
get  much  further  that  way;  the  nature  of  the  external 
world  is  inscrutable,  and  we  shall  only  plunge  into  a 
quagmire  of  indescribables.  Never  mind  what  two  tons 
refers  to;  what  is  it?  How  has  it  actually  entered  in  so 
definite  a  way  into  our  experience?  Two  tons  is  the 
reading  of  the  pointer  when  the  elephant  was  placed 
on  a  weighing-machine.  Let  us  pass  on.  "The  slope 
of  the  hill  is  6o°."     Now  the  hillside  fades  out  of  the 


252  POINTER  READINGS 

problem  and  an  angle  of  6o°  takes  its  place.  What  is 
6o°?  There  is  no  need  to  struggle  with  mystical  con- 
ceptions of  direction;  6o°  is  the  reading  of  a  plumb-line 
against  the  divisions  of  a  protractor.  Similarly  for  the 
other  data  of  the  problem.  The  softly  yielding  turf  on 
which  the  elephant  slid  is  replaced  by  a  coefficient  of 
friction,  which  though  perhaps  not  direcdy  a  pointer 
reading  is  of  kindred  nature.  No  doubt  there  are  more 
roundabout  ways  used  in  practice  for  determining  the 
weights  of  elephants  and  the  slopes  of  hills,  but  these 
are  justified  because  it  is  known  that  they  give  the  same 
results  as  direct  pointer  readings. 

And  so  we  see  that  the  poetry  fades  out  of  the  prob- 
lem, and  by  the  time  the  serious  application  of  exact 
science  begins  we  are  left  with  only  pointer  readings. 
If  then  only  pointer  readings  or  their  equivalents  are 
put  into  the  machine  of  scientific  calculation,  how  can 
we  grind  out  anything  but  pointer  readings?  But  that 
is  just  what  we  do  grind  out.  The  question  presumably 
was  to  find  the  time  of  descent  of  the  elephant,  and  the 
answer  is  a  pointer  reading  on  the  seconds'  dial  of  our 
watch. 

The  triumph  of  exact  science  in  the  foregoing  problem 
consisted  in  establishing  a  numerical  connection  between 
the  pointer  reading  of  the  weighing-machine  in  one 
experiment  on  the  elephant  and  the  pointer  reading  of 
the  watch  in  another  experiment.  And  when  we  examine 
critically  other  problems  of  physics  we  find  that  this  is 
typical.  The  whole  subject-matter  of  exact  science 
consists  of  pointer  readings  and  similar  indications. 
We  cannot  enter  here  into  the  definition  of  what  are 
to  be  classed  as  similar  indications.  The  observation  of 
approximate  coincidence  of  the  pointer  with  a  scale- 
division    can    generally    be     extended     to     include     the 


NATURE  OF  EXACT  SCIENCE  253 

observation  of  any  kind  of  coincidence — or,  as  it  is 
usually  expressed  in  the  language  of  the  general  rela- 
tivity theory,  an  intersection  of  world-lines.  The 
essential  point  is  that,  although  we  seem  to  have  very 
definite  conceptions  of  objects  in  the  external  world, 
those  conceptions  do  not  enter  into  exact  science  and 
are  not  in  any  way  confirmed  by  it.  Before  exact  science 
can  begin  to  handle  the  problem  they  must  be  replaced 
by  quantities  representing  the  results  of  physical  meas- 
urement. 

Perhaps  you  will  object  that  although  only  the  pointer 
readings  enter  into  the  actual  calculation  it  would  make 
nonsense  of  the  problem  to  leave  out  all  reference  to 
anything  else.  The  problem  necessarily  involves  some 
kind  of  connecting  background.  It  was  not  the  pointer 
reading  of  the  weighing-machine  that  slid  down  the 
hill!  And  yet  from  the  point  of  view  of  exact  science  the 
thing  that  really  did  descend  the  hill  can  only  be  de- 
scribed as  a  bundle  of  pointer  readings.  (It  should  be 
remembered  that  the  hill  also  has  been  replaced  by 
pointer  readings,  and  the  sliding  down  is  no  longer  an 
active  adventure  but  a  functional  relation  of  space  and 
time  measures.)  The  word  elephant  calls  up  a  certain 
association  of  mental  impressions,  but  it  is  clear  that 
mental  impressions  as  such  cannot  be  the  subject 
handled  in  the  physical  problem.  We  have,  for  example, 
an  impression  of  bulkiness.  To  this  there  is  presumably 
some  direct  counterpart  in  the  external  world,  but  that 
counterpart  must  be  of  a  nature  beyond  our  appre- 
hension, and  science  can  make  nothing  of  it.  Bulkiness 
enters  into  exact  science  by  yet  another  substitution; 
we  replace  it  by  a  series  of  readings  of  a  pair  of  cali- 
pers. Similarly  the  greyish  black  appearance  in  our 
mental  impression  is  replaced  in  exact  science  by  the  read- 


254  POINTER  READINGS 

ings  of  a  photometer  for  various  wave-lengths  of  light. 
And  so  on  until  all  the  characteristics  of  the  elephant 
are  exhausted  and  it  has  become  reduced  to  a  schedule 
of  measures.  There  is  always  the  triple  correspond- 
ence— 

(a)  a  mental  image,  which  is  in  our  minds  and  not  in 
the  external  world; 

(b)  some  kind  of  counterpart  in  the  external  world, 
which  is  of  inscrutable  nature; 

(<:)  a  set  of  pointer  readings,  which  exact  science  can 
study  and  connect  with  other  pointer  readings. 

And  so  we  have  our  schedule  of  pointer  readings 
ready  to  make  the  descent.  And  if  you  still  think  that 
this  substitution  has  taken  away  all  reality  from  the 
problem,  I  am  not  sorry  that  you  should  have  a  foretaste 
of  the  difficulty  in  store  for  those  who  hold  that  exact 
science  is  all-sufficient  for  the  description  of  the  universe 
and  that  there  is  nothing  in  our  experience  which  cannot 
be  brought  within  its  scope. 

I  should  like  to  make  it  clear  that  the  limitation  of 
the  scope  of  physics  to  pointer  readings  and  the  like  is 
not  a  philosophical  craze  of  my  own  but  is  essentially 
the  current  scientific  doctrine.  It  is  the  outcome  of  a 
tendency  discernible  far  back  in  the  last  century  but 
only  formulated  comprehensively  with  the  advent  of 
the  relativity  theory.  The  vocabulary  of  the  physicist 
comprises  a  number  of  words  such  as  length,  angle, 
velocity,  force,  potential,  current,  etc.,  which  we  call 
"physical  quantities".  It  is  now  recognised  as  essential 
that  these  should  be  defined  according  to  the  way  in 
which  we  actually  recognise  them  when  confronted  with 
them,  and  not  according  to  the  metaphysical  significance 
which  we  may  have  anticipated  for  them.  In  the  old 
textbooks    mass   was    defined    as    "quantity   of  matter"; 


NATURE  OF  EXACT  SCIENCE  255 

but  when  it  came  to  an  actual  determination  of  mass,  an 
experimental  method  was  prescribed  which  had  no 
bearing  on  this  definition.  The  belief  that  the  quantity 
determined  by  the  accepted  method  of  measurement 
represented  the  quantity  of  matter  in  the  object  was 
merely  a  pious  opinion.  At  the  present  day  there  is  no 
sense  in  which  the  quantity  of  matter  in  a  pound  of  lead 
can  be  said  to  be  equal  to  the  quantity  in  a  pound  of 
sugar.  Einstein's  theory  makes  a  clean  sweep  of  these 
pious  opinions,  and  insists  that  each  physical  quantity 
should  be  defined  as  the  result  of  certain  operations  of 
measurement  and  calculation.  You  may  if  you  like 
think  of  mass  as  something  of  inscrutable  nature  to 
which  the  pointer  reading  has  a  kind  of  relevance.  But 
in  physics  at  least  there  is  nothing  much  to  be  gained 
by  this  mystification,  because  it  is  the  pointer  reading 
itself  which  is  handled  in  exact  science;  and  if  you 
embed  it  in  something  of  a  more  transcendental  nature, 
you  have  only  the  extra  trouble  of  digging  it  out 
again. 

It  is  quite  true  that  when  we  say  the  mass  is  two  tons 
we  have  not  specially  in  mind  the  reading  of  the  particu- 
lar machine  on  which  the  weighing  was  carried  out. 
That  is  because  we  do  not  start  to  tackle  the  problem  of 
the  elephant's  escapade  ab  initio  as  though  it  were  the 
first  inquiry  we  had  ever  made  into  the  phenomena  of 
the  external  world.  The  examiner  would  have  had  to  be 
much  more  explicit  if  he  had  not  presumed  a  general 
acquaintance  with  the  elementary  laws  of  physics,  i.e. 
laws  which  permit  us  to  deduce  the  readings  of  other 
indicators  from  the  reading  of  one.  //  is  this  connec- 
tivity of  pointer  readings,  expressed  by  physical  laws, 
which  supplies  the  continuous  background  that  any  realis- 
tic problem  demands. 


256  POINTER  READINGS 

It  is  obviously  one  of  the  conditions  of  the  problem 
that  the  same  elephant  should  be  concerned  in  the 
weighing  experiment  and  in  the  tobogganing  experi- 
ment. How  can  this  identity  be  expressed  in  a  descrip- 
tion of  the  world  by  pointer  readings  only?  Two 
readings  may  be  equal,  but  it  is  meaningless  to  inquire 
if  they  are  identical;  if  then  the  elephant  is  a  bundle  of 
pointer  readings,  how  can  we  ask  whether  it  is  continu- 
ally the  identical  bundle  ?  The  examiner  does  not  confide 
to  us  how  the  identity  of  the  elephant  was  ensured;  we 
have  only  his  personal  guarantee  that  there  was  no 
substitution.  Perhaps  the  creature  answered  to  its  name 
on  both  occasions;  if  so  the  test  of  identity  is  clearly 
outside  the  present  domain  of  physics.  The  only  test 
lying  purely  in  the  domain  of  physics  is  that  of  con- 
tinuity; the  elephant  must  be  watched  all  the  way  from 
the  scales  to  the  hillside.  The  elephant,  we  must  remem- 
ber, is  a  tube  in  the  four-dimensional  world  demarcated 
from  the  rest  of  space-time  by  a  more  or  less  abrupt 
boundary.  Using  the  retina  of  his  eye  as  an  indicator 
and  making  frequent  readings  of  the  oudine  of  the 
image,  the  observer  satisfied  himself  that  he  was  fol- 
lowing one  continuous  and  isolated  world-tube  from 
beginning  to  end.  If  his  vigilance  was  intermittent  he 
took  a  risk  of  substitution,  and  consequently  a  risk  of 
the  observed  time  of  descent  failing  to  agree  with  the 
time  calculated.*  Note  that  we  do  not  infer  that  there 
is  any  identity  of  the  contents  of  the  isolated  world-tube 
throughout  its  length;  such  identity  would  be  meaning- 

*  A  good  illustration  of  such  substitution  is  afforded  by  astronomical 
observations  of  a  certain  double  star  with  two  components  of  equal 
brightness.  After  an  intermission  of  observation  the  two  components 
were  inadvertently  interchanged,  and  the  substitution  was  not  detected 
until  the  increasing  discrepancy  between  the  actual  and  predicted  orbits 
was  inquired  into. 


LIMITS  OF  PHYSICAL  KNOWLEDGE  257 

less  in  physics.  We  use  instead  the  law  of  conserva- 
tion of  mass  (either  as  an  empirical  law  or  deduced 
from  the  law  of  gravitation)  which  assures  us  that, 
provided  the  tube  is  isolated,  the  pointer  reading  on 
the  schedule  derived  from  the  weighing-machine  type 
of  experiment  has  a  constant  value  along  the  tube. 
For  the  purpose  of  exact  science  "the  same  object" 
becomes  replaced  by  "isolated  world-tube".  The  con- 
stancy of  certain  properties  of  the  elephant  is  not 
assumed  as  self-evident  from  its  sameness,  but  is  an 
inference  from  experimental  and  theoretical  laws  re- 
lating to  world-tubes  which  are  accepted  as  well 
established. 

Limitations  of  Physical  Knowledge,  Whenever  we  state 
the  properties  of  a  body  in  terms  of  physical  quantities 
we  are  imparting  knowledge  as  to  the  response  of 
various  metrical  indicators  to  its  presence,  and  nothing 
more.  After  all,  knowledge  of  this  kind  is  fairly  com- 
prehensive. A  knowledge  of  the  response  of  all  kinds 
of  objects — weighing-machines  and  other  indicators — 
would  determine  completely  its  relation  to  its  environ- 
ment, leaving  only  its  inner  un-get-atable  nature  un- 
determined. In  the  relativity  theory  we  accept  this  as 
full  knowledge,  the  nature  of  an  object  in  so  far  as  it  is 
ascertainable  by  scientific  inquiry  being  the  abstraction 
of  its  relations  to  all  surrounding  objects.  The  progress 
of  the  relativity  theory  has  been  largely  due  to  the 
development  of  a  powerful  mathematical  calculus  for 
dealing  compendiously  with  an  infinite  scheme  of 
pointer  readings,  and  the  technical  term  tensor  used  so 
largely  in  treatises  on  Einstein's  theory  may  be  translated 
schedule  of  pointer  readings.  It  is  part  of  the  aesthetic 
appeal  of  the  mathematical  theory  of  relativity  that  the 


258  POINTER  READINGS 

mathematics  is  so  closely  adapted  to  the  physical  con- 
ceptions. It  is  not  so  in  all  subjects.  For  example,  we 
may  admire  the  triumph  of  patience  of  the  mathemati- 
cian in  predicting  so  closely  the  positions  of  the  moon, 
but  aesthetically  the  lunar  theory  is  atrocious;  it  is 
obvious  that  the  moon  and  the  mathematician  use  dif- 
ferent methods  of  finding  the  lunar  orbit.  But  by  the 
use  of  tensors  the  mathematical  physicist  precisely  de- 
scribes the  nature  of  his  subject-matter  as  a  schedule  of 
indicator  readings;  and  those  accretions  of  images  and 
conceptions  which  have  no  place  in  physical  science  are 
automatically  dismissed. 

The  recognition  that  our  knowledge  of  the  objects 
treated  in  physics  consists  solely  of  readings  of  pointers 
and  other  indicators  transforms  our  view  of  the  status 
of  physical  knowledge  in  a  fundamental  way.  Until 
recently  it  was  taken  for  granted  that  we  had  knowledge 
of  a  much  more  intimate  kind  of  the  entities  of  the  ex- 
ternal world.  Let  me  give  an  illustration  which  takes 
us  to  the  root  of  the  great  problem  of  the  relations 
of  matter  and  spirit.  Take  the  living  human  brain 
endowed  with  mind  and  thought.  Thought  is  one  of  the 
indisputable  facts  of  the  world.  I  know  that  I  think, 
with  a  certainty  which  I  cannot  attribute  to  any  of  my 
physical  knowledge  of  the  world.  More  hypothetically, 
but  pn  fairly  plausible  evidence,  I  am  convinced  that 
you  have  minds  which  think.  Here  then  is  a  world  fact 
to  be  investigated.  The  physicist  brings  his  tools  and 
commences  systematic  exploration.  All  that  he  dis- 
covers is  a  collection  of  atoms  and  electrons  and  fields  of 
force  arranged  in  space  and  time,  apparently  similar  to 
those  found  in  inorganic  objects.  He  may  trace  other 
physical  characteristics,  energy,  temperature,  entropy. 
None  of  these  is  identical  with  thought.     He  might  set 


LIMITS  OF  PHYSICAL  KNOWLEDGE         259 

down  thought  as  an  illusion — some  perverse  interpreta- 
tion of  the  interplay  of  the  physical  entities  that  he  has 
found.  Or  if  he  sees  the  folly  of  calling  the  most  un- 
doubted element  of  our  experience  an  illusion,  he  will 
have  to  face  the  tremendous  question,  How  can  this  col- 
lection of  ordinary  atoms  be  a  thinking  machine?  But 
what  knowledge  have  we  of  the  nature  of  atoms  which 
renders  it  at  all  incongruous  that  they  should  constitute 
a  thinking  object?  The  Victorian  physicist  felt  that  he 
knew  just  what  he  was  talking  about  when  he  used  such 
terms  as  matter  and  atoms.  Atoms  were  tiny  billiard 
balls,  a  crisp  statement  that  was  supposed  to  tell  you 
all  about  their  nature  in  a  way  which  could  never  be 
achieved  for  transcendental  things  like  consciousness, 
beauty  or  humour.  But  now  we  realise  that  science  has 
nothing  to  say  as  to  the  intrinsic  nature  of  the  atom.  The 
physical  atom  is,  like  everything  else  in  physics,  a 
schedule  of  pointer  readings.  The  schedule  is,  we  agree, 
attached  to  some  unknown  background.  Why  not  then 
attach  it  to  something  of  spiritual  nature  of  which  a 
prominent  characteristic  is  thought.  It  seems  rather  silly 
to  prefer  to  attach  it  to  something  of  a  so-called  "con- 
crete" nature  inconsistent  with  thought,  and  then  to 
wonder  where  the  thought  comes  from.  We  have  dis- 
missed all  preconception  as  to  the  background  of  our 
pointer  readings,  and  for  the  most  part  we  can  discover 
nothing  as  to  its  nature.  But  in  one  case — namely,  for 
the  pointer  readings  of  my  own  brain — I  have  an  in- 
sight which  is  not  limited  to  the  evidence  of  the  pointer 
readings.  That  insight  shows  that  they  are  attached  to 
a  background  of  consciousness.  Although  I  may  expect 
that  the  background  of  other  pointer  readings  in  physics 
is  of  a  nature  continuous  with  that  revealed  to  me  in  this 
particular  case,  I  do  not  suppose  that  it  always  has  the 


260  POINTER  READINGS 

more  specialised  attributes  of  consciousness.*  But  in 
regard  to  my  one  piece  of  insight  into  the  background 
no  problem  of  irreconcilability  arises;  I  have  no  other 
knowledge  of  the  background  with  which  to  reconcile  it. 
In  science  we  study  the  linkage  of  pointer  readings 
with  pointer  readings.  The  terms  link  together  in  endless 
cycle  with  the  same  inscrutable  nature  running  through 
the  whole.  There  is  nothing  to  prevent  the  assemblage 
of  atoms  constituting  a  brain  from  being  of  itself  a 
thinking  object  in  virtue  of  that  nature  which  physics 
leaves  undetermined  and  undeterminable.  If  we  must 
embed  our  schedule  of  indicator  readings  in  some  kind 
of  background,  at  least  let  us  accept  the  only  hint  we 
have  received  as  to  the  significance  of  the  background — 
namely  that  it  has  a  nature  capable  of  manifesting  itself 
as  mental  activity. 

Cyclic  Method  of  Physics.  I  must  explain  this  reference 
to  an  endless  cycle  of  physical  terms.  I  will  refer  again 
to  Einstein's  law  of  gravitation.  I  have  already  ex- 
pounded it  to  you  more  than  once  and  I  hope  you  gained 
some  idea  of  it  from  the  explanation.  This  time  I  am 
going  to  expound  it  in  a  way  so  complete  that  there  is 
not  much  likelihood  that  anyone  will  understand  it. 
Never  mind.  We  are  not  now  seeking  further  light  on 
the    cause    of   gravitation;    we    are    interested  in   seeing 

*  For  example,  we  should  most  of  us  assume  (hypothetically)  that 
the  dynamical  quality  of  the  world  referred  to  in  chapter  v  is  characteris- 
tic of  the  whole  background.  Apparently  it  is  not  to  be  found  in  the 
pointer  readings,  and  our  only  insight  into  it  is  in  the  feeling  of  "becom- 
ing" in  our  consciousness.  "Becoming"  like  "reasoning"  is  known  to  us 
only  through  its  occurrence  in  our  own  minds;  but  whereas  it  would  be 
absurd  to  suppose  that  the  latter  extends  to  inorganic  aggregations  of 
atoms,  the  former  may  be  (and  commonly  is)  extended  to  the  inorganic 
world,  so  that  it  is  not  a  matter  of  indifference  whether  the  progress  of 
the  inorganic  world  is  viewed  from  past  to  future  or  from  future  to  past. 


CYCLIC  METHOD  OF  PHYSICS  261 

what  would  really  be  involved  in  a  complete  explanation 
of  anything  physical. 

Einstein's  law  in  its  analytical  form  is  a  statement  that 
in  empty  space  certain  quantities  called  potentials  obey 
certain  lengthy  differential  equations.  We  make  a 
memorandum  of  the  word  ''potential"  to  remind  us 
that  we  must  later  on  explain  what  it  means.  We  might 
conceive  a  world  in  which  the  potentials  at  every  moment 
and  every  place  had  quite  arbitrary  values.  The  actual 
world  is  not  so  unlimited,  the  potentials  being  restricted 
to  those  values  which  conform  to  Einstein's  equations. 
The  next  question  is,  What  are  potentials?  They  can 
be  defined  as  quantities  derived  by  quite  simple  mathe- 
matical calculations  from  certain  fundamental  quantities 
called  intervals.  (Mem.  Explain  "interval".)  If  we 
know  the  values  of  the  various  intervals  throughout  the 
world  definite  rules  can  be  given  for  deriving  the  values 
of  the  potentials.  What  are  intervals?  They  are  rela- 
tions between  pairs  of  events  which  can  be  measured  with 
a  scale  or  a  clock  or  with  both.  (Mem.  Explain  "scale" 
and  "clock".)  Instructions  can  be  given  for  the  correct 
use  of  the  scale  and  clock  so  that  the  interval  is  given  by 
a  prescribed  combination  of  their  readings.  What  are 
scales  and  clocks?  A  scale  is  a  graduated  strip  of  mat- 
ter which.  .  .  .  (Mem.  Explain  "matter".)  On  second 
thoughts  I  will  leave  the  rest  of  the  description  as  "an 
exercise  to  the  reader"  since  \t  would  take  rather  a  long 
time  to  enumerate  all  the  properties  and  niceties  of 
behaviour  of  the  material  standard  which  a  physicist 
would  accept  as  a  perfect  scale  or  a  perfect  clock.  We 
pass  on  to  the  next  question,  What  is  matter?  We  have 
dismissed  the  metaphysical  conception  of  substance.  We 
might  perhaps  here  describe  the  atomic  and  electrical 
structure  of   matter,  but  that  leads  to  the  microscopic 


262  POINTER  READINGS 

aspects  of  the  world,  whereas  we  are  here  taking  the 
macroscopic  outlook.  Confining  ourselves  to  mechanics, 
which  is  the  subject  in  which  the  law  of  gravitation 
arises,  matter  may  be  defined  as  the  embodiment  of  three 
related  physical  quantities,  mass  (or  energy),  momentum 
and  stress.  What  are  "mass",  "momentum"  and 
"stress"?  It  is  one  of  the  most  far-reaching  achieve- 
ments of  Einstein's  theory  that  it  has  given  an  exact 
answer  to  this  question.  They  are  rather  formidable 
looking  expressions  containing  the  potentials  and  their 
first  and  second  derivatives  with  respect  to  the  co- 
ordinates. What  are  the  potentials?  Why,  that  is  just 
what  I  have  been  explaining  to  you! 

The  definitions  of  physics  proceed  according  to  the 
method  immortalised  in  "The  House  that  Jack  built" : 
This  is  the  potential,  that  was  derived  from  the  interval, 
that  was  measured  by  the  scale,  that  was  made  from  the 
matter,  that  embodied  the  stress,  that.  .  .  .  But  instead 
of  finishing  with  Jack,  whom  of  course  every  youngster 
must  know  without  need  for  an  introduction,  we  make 
a  circuit  back  to  the  beginning  of  the  rhyme:  .  .  .  that 
worried  the  cat,  that  killed  the  rat,  that  ate  the  malt, 
that  lay  in  the  house,  that  was  built  by  the  priest  all 
shaven  and  shorn,  that  married  the  man.  .  .  .  Now  we 
can  go  round  and  round  for  ever. 

But  perhaps  you  have  already  cut  short  my  explana- 
tion of  gravitation.  When  we  reached  matter  you  had 
had  enough  of  it.  "Please  do  not  explain  any  more, 
I  happen  to  know  what  matter  is."  Very  well;  matter 
is  something  that  Mr.  X  knows.  Let  us  see  how  it  goes : 
This  is  the  potential  that  was  derived  from  the  interval 
that  was  measured  by  the  scale  that  was  made  from  the 
matter  that  Mr.  X  knows.  Next  question,  What  is  Mr.  X? 

Well,  it  happens  that  physics  is  not  at  all  anxious  to 


CYCLIC  METHOD  OF  PHYSICS  263 

pursue  the  question,  What  is  Mr.  X?  It  is  not  disposed 
to  admit  that  its  elaborate  structure  of  a  physical  uni- 
verse is  ''The  House  that  Mr.  X  built".  It  looks  upon 
Mr.  X — and  more  particularly  the  part  of  Mr.  X  that 
knows — as  a  rather  troublesome  tenant  who  at  a  late 
stage    of   the    world's    history   has    come    to    inhabit   a 

Potential 


Stress  m  •Interval 


Matter  •  < •  Scale 


Mr.  X  • 


Fig.  8 

structure  which  inorganic  Nature  has  by  slow  evolutionary 
progress  contrived  to  build.  And  so  it  turns  aside  from 
the  avenue  leading  to  Mr.  X — and  beyond — and  closes 
up  its  cycle  leaving  him  out  in  the  cold. 

From  its  own  point  of  view  physics  is  entirely  jus- 
tified. That  matter  in  some  indirect  way  comes  within 
the  purview  of  Mr.  X's  mind  is  not  a  fact  of  any  utility 


264  POINTER  READINGS 

for  a  theoretical  scheme  of  physics.  We  cannot  embody 
it  in  a  differential  equation.  It  is  ignored;  and  the 
physical  properties  of  matter  and  other  entities  are 
expressed  by  their  linkages  in  the  cycle.  And  you  can 
see  how  by  the  ingenious  device  of  the  cycle  physics 
secures  for  itself  a  self-contained  domain  for  study  with 
no  loose  ends  projecting  into  the  unknown.  All  other 
physical  definitions  have  the  same  kind  of  interlocking. 
Electric  force  is  defined  as  something  which  causes 
motion  of  an  electric  charge ;  an  electric  charge  is  some- 
thing which  exerts  electric  force.  So  that  an  electric 
charge  is  something  that  exerts  something  that  produces 
motion  of  something  that  exerts  something  that  produces 
.   .   .   ad  infinitum. 

But  I  am  not  now  writing  of  pure  physics,  and  from 
a  broader  standpoint  I  do  not  see  how  we  can  leave  out 
Mr.  X.  The  fact  that  matter  is  "knowable  to  Mr.  X" 
must  be  set  down  as  one  of  the  fundamental  attributes 
of  matter.  I  do  not  say  that  it  is  very  distinctive,  since 
other  entities  of  physics  are  also  knowable  to  him;  but 
the  potentiality  of  the  whole  physical  world  for  awaking 
impressions  in  consciousness  is  an  attribute  not  to  be 
ignored  when  we  compare  the  actual  world  with  worlds 
which,  we  fancy,  might  have  been  created.  There  seems 
to  be  a  prevalent  disposition  to  minimise  the  importance 
of  this.  The  attitude  is  that  "knowableness  to  Mr.  X" 
is  a  negligible  attribute,  because  Mr.  X  is  so  clever  that 
he  could  know  pretty  much  anything  that  there  was  to 
know.  I  have  already  urged  the  contrary  view — that 
there  is  a  definitely  selective  action  of  the  mind;  and 
since  physics   treats   of  what  is  knowable  to   mind  *   its 

*  This  is  obviously  true  of  all  experimental  physics,  and  must  be 
true  of  theoretical  physics  if  it  is  (as  it  professes  to  be)  based  on  experi- 
ment. 


ACTUALITY  265 

subject-matter   has   undergone,    and   indeed   retains   evi- 
dences of,  this  process  of  selection. 

Actuality.      "Knowableness    to    mind"    is    moreover    a 
property  which   differentiates   the   actual   world    of   our 
experience    from   imaginary  worlds    in  which   the    same 
general    laws    of    Nature    are    supposed    to    hold    true. 
Consider  a  world — Utopia,  let  us  say — governed  by  all 
the  laws  of  Nature  known  and  unknown  which  govern 
our    own    world,    but    containing    better    stars,    planets, 
cities,    animals,    etc. — a    world    which    might    exist,    but 
it  just  happens  that  it  doesn't.     How  can  the  physicist 
test  that  Utopia  is  not  the  actual  world?     We  refer  to 
a  piece  of  matter  in  it;  it  is  not  real  matter  but  it  attracts 
any  other  piece  of  (unreal)  matter  in  Utopia  according 
to  the  law  of  gravitation.     Scales  and  clocks  constructed 
of  this  unreal  matter  will  measure  wrong  intervals,  but 
the  physicist  cannot  detect  that  they  are  wrong  unless 
he  has  first  shown  the  unreality  of  the  matter.     As  soon 
as  any  element  in  it  has  been  shown  to  be  unreal  Utopia 
collapses;  but  so  long  as  we  keep  to  the  cycles  of  physics 
we  can  never  find  the  vulnerable  point,  for  each  element 
is  correctly  linked  to  the  rest  of  the  cycle,  all  our  laws 
of  Nature  expressed  by  the  cycle  being  obeyed  in  Utopia 
by  hypothesis.     The  unreal  stars  emit  unreal  light  which 
falls    on   unreal    retinas    and    ultimately    reaches    unreal 
brains.    The  next  step  takes  it  outside  the  cycle  and  gives 
the   opportunity   of   exposing   the   whole   deception.      Is 
the    brain    disturbance    translated    into     consciousness? 
That  will  test  whether  the  brain  is  real  or  unreal.    There 
is   no   question   about   consciousness   being   real  or  not; 
consciousness  is  self-knowing  and  the  epithet  real  adds 
nothing    to    that.      Of    the    infinite    number    of    worlds 
which  are  examples  of  what  might  be  possible  under  the 


266  POINTER  READINGS 

laws  of  Nature,  there  is  one  which  does  something  more 
than  fulfil  those  laws  of  Nature.  This  property,  which 
is  evidently  not  definable  with  respect  to  any  of  the  laws 
of  Nature,  we  describe  as  "actuality" — generally  using 
the  word  as  a  kind  of  halo  of  indefinite  import.  We 
have  seen  that  the  trend  of  modern  physics  is  to  reject 
these  indefinite  attributions  and  to  define  its  terms 
according  to  the  way  in  which  we  recognise  the  pro- 
perties wThen  confronted  by  them.  We  recognise  the 
actuality  of  a  particular  world  because  it  is  that  world 
alone  with  which  consciousness  interacts.  However 
much  the  theoretical  physicist  may  dislike  a  reference  to 
consciousness,  the  experimental  physicist  uses  freely 
this  touchstone  of  actuality.  He  would  perhaps  prefer 
to  believe  that  his  instruments  and  observations  are  certi- 
fied as  actual  by  his  material  sense  organs;  but  the  final 
guarantor  is  the  mind  that  comes  to  know  the  indications 
of  the  material  organs.  Each  of  us  is  armed  with  this 
touchstone  of  actuality;  by  applying  it  we  decide  that 
this  sorry  world  of  ours  is  actual  and  Utopia  is  a  dream. 
As  our  individual  consciousnesses  are  different,  so  our 
touchstones  are  different;  but  fortunately  they  all  agree 
in  their  indication  of  actuality — or  at  any  rate  those 
which  agree  are  in  sufficient  majority  to  shut  the  others 
up  in  lunatic  asylums. 

It  is  natural  that  theoretical  physics  in  its  formulation 
of  a  general  scheme  of  law  should  leave  out  of  account 
actuality  and  the  guarantor  of  actuality.  For  it  is  just 
this  omission  which  makes  the  difference  between  a  law 
of  Nature  and  a  particular  sequence  of  events.  That 
which  is  possible  (or  not  "too  improbable")  is  the 
domain  of  natural  science;  that  which  is  actual  is  the 
domain  of  natural  history.  We  need  scarcely  add  that 
the  contemplation  in  natural  science  of  a  wider  domain 


ACTUALITY  267 

than  the  actual  leads  to  a   far  better  understanding  of 
the  actual. 

From  a  broader  point  of  view  than  that  of  elaborating 
the  physical  scheme  of  law  we  cannot  treat  the  connection 
with  mind  as  merely  an  incident  in  a  self-existent  inor- 
ganic world.      In  saying  that  the  differentiation  of  the 
actual  from  the  non-actual  is  only  expressible  by  reference 
to  mind  I  do  not  mean  to  imply  that  a  universe  without 
conscious  mind  would  have  no  more  status  than  Utopia. 
But  its  property  of  actuality  would  be  indefinable  since 
the  one  approach  to  a  definition  is  cut  off.     The  actuality 
of  Nature  is  like  the  beauty  of  Nature.    We  can  scarcely 
describe  the  beauty  of  a  landscape  as  non-existent  when 
there  is  no  conscious  being  to  witness  it;  but  it  is  through 
consciousness    that   we    can    attribute    a    meaning   to    it. 
And  so  it  is  with  the  actuality  of  the  world.     If  actuality 
means  "known  to  mind"   then  it  is  a  purely  subjective 
character  of  the  world;  to  make  it  objective  we  must 
substitute  "knowable  to  mind".     The  less  stress  we  lay 
on  the  accident  of  parts  of  the  world  being  known  at 
the  present  era  to  particular  minds,  the  more  stress  we 
must  lay  on  the  potentiality  of  being  known  to  mind  as 
a    fundamental   objective  property   of  matter,   giving  it 
the  status  of  actuality  whether  individual  consciousness 
is  taking  note  of  it  or  not. 

In  the  diagram  Mr.  X  has  been  linked  to  the  cycle  at 
a  particular  point  in  deference  to  his  supposed  claim 
that  he  knows  matter;  but  a  little  reflection  will  show 
that  the  point  of  contact  of  mind  with  the  physical 
universe  is  not  very  definite.  Mr.  X  knows  a  table;  but 
the  point  of  contact  with  his  mind  is  not  in  the  material 
of  the  table.  Light  waves  are  propagated  from  the 
table  to  the  eye;  chemical  changes  occur  in  the  retina; 
propagation  of   some   kind  occurs   in  the  optic  nerves; 


268  POINTER  READINGS 

atomic  changes  follow  in  the  brain.  Just  where  the 
final  leap  into  consciousness  occurs  is  not  clear.  We  do 
not  know  the  last  stage  of  the  message  in  the  physical 
world  before  it  became  a  sensation  in  consciousness. 
This  makes  no  difference.  The  physical  entities  have 
a  cyclic  connection,  and  whatever  intrinsic  nature  we 
attribute  to  one  of  them  runs  as  a  background  through 
the  whole  cycle.  It  is  not  a  question  whether  matter  or 
electricity  or  potential  is  the  direct  stimulus  to  the  mind; 
in  their  physical  aspects  these  are  equally  represented 
as  pointer  readings  or  schedules  of  pointer  readings. 
According  to  our  discussion  of  world  building  they  are 
the  measures  of  structure  arising  from  the  comparability 
of  certain  aspects  of  the  basal  relations — measures  which 
by  no  means  exhaust  the  significance  of  those  relations. 
I  do  not  believe  that  the  activity  of  matter  at  a  certain 
point  of  the  brain  stimulates  an  activity  of  mind;  my 
view  is  that  in  the  activity  of  matter  there  is  a  metrical 
description  of  certain  aspects  of  the  activity  of  mind. 
The  activity  of  the  matter  is  our  way  of  recognising  a 
combination  of  the  measures  of  structure;  the  activity 
of  the  mind  is  our  insight  into  the  complex  of  relations 
whose  comparability  gives  the  foundation  of  those 
measures. 

"What  is  Mr.  X?"  In  the  light  of  these  considerations 
let  us  now  see  what  we  can  make  of  the  question,  What 
is  Mr.  X?  I  must  undertake  the  inquiry  single-handed; 
I  cannot  avail  myself  of  your  collaboration  without  first 
answering  or  assuming  an  answer  to  the  equally  difficult 
question,  What  are  you?  Accordingly  the  whole  in- 
quiry must  take  place  in  the  domain  of  my  own  con- 
sciousness. I  find  there  certain  data  purporting  to 
relate  to  this  unknown  X;  and  I  can   (by  using  powers 


"WHAT  IS  MR.  X?"  269 

which  respond  to  my  volition)  extend  the  data,  i.e.  I  can 
perform  experiments  on  X.  For  example  I  can  make 
a  chemical  analysis.  The  immediate  result  of  these 
experiments  is  the  occurrence  of  certain  visual  or 
olfactory  sensations  in  my  consciousness.  Clearly  it  is 
a  long  stride  from  these  sensations  to  any  rational  in- 
ference about  Mr.  X.  For  example,  I  learn  that  Mr.  X 
has  carbon  in  his  brain,  but  the  immediate  knowledge 
was  of  something  (not  carbon)  in  my  own  mind.  The 
reason  why  I,  on  becoming  aware  of  something  in  my 
mind,  can  proceed  to  assert  knowledge  of  something 
elsewhere,  is  because  there  is  a  systematic  scheme  of 
inference  which  can  be  traced  from  the  one  item  of 
knowledge  to  the  other.  Leaving  aside  instinctive  or 
commonsense  inference — the  crude  precursor  of  scien- 
tific inference — the  inference  follows  a  linkage,  which 
can  only  be  described  symbolically,  extending  from  the 
point  in  the  symbolic  world  where  I  locate  myself  to  the 
point  where  I  locate  Mr.  X. 

One  feature  of  this  inference  is  that  I  never  discover 
what  carbon  really  is.  It  remains  a  symbol.  There  is 
carbon  in  my  own  brain-mind;  but  the  self-knowledge 
of  my  mind  does  not  reveal  this  to  me.  I  can  only  know 
that  the  symbol  for  carbon  must  be  placed  there  by 
following  a  route  of  inference  through  the  external 
world  similar  to  that  used  in  discovering  it  in  Mr.  X;  and 
however  closely  associated  this  carbon  may  be  with  my 
thinking  powers,  it  is  as  a  symbol  divorced  from  any 
thinking  capacity  that  I  learn  of  its  existence.  Carbon 
is  a  symbol  definable  only  in  terms  of  the  other  symbols 
belonging  to  the  cyclic  scheme  of  physics.  What  I  have 
discovered  is  that,  in  order  that  the  symbols  describing 
the  physical  world  may  conform  to  the  mathematical 
formulae  which  they  are  designed  to  obey,  it  is  necessary 


270  POINTER  READINGS 

to  place  the  symbol  for  carbon  (amongst  others)  in  the 
locality  of  Mr.  X.  By  similar  means  I  can  make  an 
exhaustive  physical  examination  of  Mr.  X  and  discover 
the  whole  array  of  symbols  to  be  assigned  to  his 
locality. 

Will  this  array  of  symbols  give  me  the  whole  of 
Mr.  X?  There  is  not  the  least  reason  to  think  so.  The 
voice  that  comes  to  us  over  the  telephone  wire  is  not  the 
whole  of  what  is  at  the  end  of  the  wire.  The  scientific 
linkage  is  like  the  telephone  wire;  it  can  transmit  just 
what  it  is  constructed  to  transmit  and  no  more. 

It  will  be  seen  that  the  line  of  communication  has 
two  aspects.  It  is  a  chain  of  inference  stretching  from 
the  symbols  immediately  associated  with  the  sensations 
in  my  mind  to  the  symbols  descriptive  of  Mr.  X;  and 
it  is  a  chain  of  stimuli  in  the  external  world  starting 
from  Mr.  X  and  reaching  my  brain.  Ideally  the  steps 
of  the  inference  exactly  reverse  the  steps  of  the  physical 
transmission  which  brought  the  information.  (Naturally 
we  make  many  short  cuts  in  inference  by  applying 
accumulated  experience  and  knowledge.)  Commonly 
we  think  of  it  only  in  its  second  aspect  as  a  physical 
transmission;  but  because  it  is  also  a  line  of  inference 
it  is  subject  to  limitations  which  we  should  not  necessarily 
expect  a  physical  transmission  to  conform  to. 

The  system  of  inference  employed  in  physical  in- 
vestigation reduces  to  mathematical  equations  governing 
the  symbols,  and  so  long  as  we  adhere  to  this  procedure 
we  are  limited  to  symbols  of  arithmetical  character 
appropriate  to  such  mathematical  equations.*  Thus 
there   is  no    opportunity    for   acquiring   by   any  physical 

*  The  solitary  exception  is,  I  believe,  Dirac's  generalisation  which 
introduces  g-numbers  (p.  210).  There  is  as  yet  no  approach  to  a  general 
system  of  inference  on  a  non-numerical  basis. 


"WHAT  IS  MR.  X?"  271 

investigation  a  knowledge  of  Mr.  X  other  than  that 
which  can  be  expressed  in  numerical  form  so  as  to 
be  passed  through  a  succession  of  mathematical 
equations. 

Mathematics  is  the  model  of  exact  inference;  and 
in  physics  we  have  endeavoured  to  replace  all  cruder 
inference  by  this  rigorous  type.  Where  we  cannot 
complete  the  mathematical  chain  we  confess  that  we  are 
wandering  in  the  dark  and  are  unable  to  assert  real 
knowledge.  Small  wonder  then  that  physical  science 
should  have  evolved  a  conception  of  the  world  consisting 
of  entities  rigorously  bound  to  one  another  by  mathe- 
matical equations  forming  a  deterministic  scheme.  This 
knowledge  has  all  been  inferred  and  it  was  bound  there- 
fore to  conform  to  the  system  of  inference  that  was  used. 
The  determinism  of  the  physical  laws  simply  reflects 
the  determinism  of  the  method  of  inference.  This  soulless 
nature  of  the  scientific  world  need  not  worry  those  who 
are  persuaded  that  the  main  significances  of  our  en- 
vironment are  of  a  more  spiritual  character.  Anyone 
who  studied  the  method  of  inference  employed  by  the 
physicist  could  predict  the  general  characteristics  of 
the  world  that  he  must  necessarily  find.  What  he  could 
not  have  predicted  is  the  great  success  of  the  method — 
the  submission  of  so  large  a  proportion  of  natural 
phenomena  to  be  brought  into  the  prejudged  scheme. 
But  making  all  allowance  for  future  progress  in  develop- 
ing the  scheme,  it  seems  to  be  flying  in  the  face  of 
obvious  facts  to  pretend  that  it  is  all  comprehensive, 
Mr.  X  is  one  of  the  recalcitrants.  When  sound-waves 
impinge  on  his  ear  he  moves,  not  in  accordance  with  a 
mathematical  equation  involving  the  physical  measure 
numbers  of  the  waves,  but  in  accordance  with  the 
meaning  that  those  sound-waves  are  used  to  convey.    To 


272  POINTER  READINGS 

know  what  there  is  about  Mr.  X  which  makes  him 
behave  in  this  strange  way,  we  must  look  not  to  a 
physical  system  of  inference,  but  to  that  insight  beneath 
the  symbols  which  in  our  own  minds  we  possess.  It  is 
by  this  insight  that  we  can  finally  reach  an  answer  to 
our  question,  What  is  Mr.  X? 


Chapter  XIII 

REALITY 

The  Real  and  the  Concrete.  One  of  our  ancestors,  taking 
arboreal  exercise  in  the  forest,  failed  to  reach  the  bough 
intended  and  his  hand  closed  on  nothingness.  The 
accident  might  well  occasion  philosophical  reflections 
on  the  distinctions  of  substance  and  void — to  say  nothing 
of  the  phenomenon  of  gravity.  However  that  may  be, 
his  descendants  down  to  this  day  have  come  to  be 
endowed  with  an  immense  respect  for  substance  arising 
we  know  not  how  or  why.  So  far  as  familiar  experience 
is  concerned,  substance  occupies  the  centre  of  the  stage, 
rigged  out  with  the  attributes  of  form,  colour,  hardness, 
etc.,  which  appeal  to  our  several  senses.  Behind  it  is  a 
subordinate  background  of  space  and  time  permeated 
by  forces  and  unconcrete  agencies  to  minister  to  the 
star  performer. 

Our  conception  of  substance  is  only  vivid  so  long  as 
we  do  not  face  it.  It  begins  to  fade  when  we  analyse  it. 
We  may  dismiss  many  of  its  supposed  attributes  which 
are  evidently  projections  of  our  sense-impressions  out- 
wards into  the  external  world.  Thus  the  colour  which  is 
so  vivid  to  us  is  in  our  minds  and  cannot  be  embodied 
in  a  legitimate  conception  of  the  substantial  object  itself. 
But  in  any  case  colour  is  no  part  of  the  essential  nature 
of  substance.  Its  supposed  nature  is  that  which  we  try 
to  call  to  mind  by  the  word  "concrete",  which  is 
perhaps  an  outward  projection  of  our  sense  of  touch. 

273 


274  REALITY 

When  I  try  to  abstract  from  the  bough  everything  but 
its  substance  or  concreteness  and  concentrate  on  an 
effort  to  apprehend  this,  all  ideas  elude  me;  but  the 
effort  brings  with  it  an  instinctive  tightening  of  the 
fingers — from  which  perhaps  I  might  infer  that  my 
conception  of  substance  is  not  very  different  from  my 
arboreal  ancestor's. 

So  strongly  has  substance  held  the  place  of  leading 
actor  on  the  stage  of  experience  that  in  common  usage 
concrete  and  real  are  almost  synonymous.  Ask  any  man 
who  is  not  a  philosopher  or  a  mystic  to  name  something 
typically  real;  he  is  almost  sure  to  choose  a  concrete 
thing.  Put  the  question  to  him  whether  Time  is  real; 
he  will  probably  decide  with  some  hesitation  that  it 
must  be  classed  as  real,  but  he  has  an  inner  feeling  that 
the  question  is  in  some  way  inappropriate  and  that  he  is 
being  cross-examined  unfairly. 

In  the  scientific  world  the  conception  of  substance 
is  wholly  lacking,  and  that  which  most  nearly  replaces 
it,  viz.  electric  charge,  is  not  exalted  as  star-performer 
above  the  other  entities  of  physics.  For  this  reason  the 
scientific  world  often  shocks  us  by  its  appearance  of 
unreality.  It  offers  nothing  to  satisfy  our  demand  for 
the  concrete.  How  should  it,  when  we  cannot  formu- 
late that  demand?  I  tried  to  formulate  it;  but  nothing 
resulted  save  a  tightening  of  the  fingers.  Science  does 
not  overlook  the  provision  for  tactual  and  muscular 
sensation.  In  leading  us  away  from  the  concrete,  science 
is  reminding  us  that  our  contact  with  the  real  is  more 
varied  than  was  apparent  to  the  ape-mind,  to  whom  the 
bough  which  supported  him  typified  the  beginning  and 
end  of  reality. 

It  is  not  solely  the  scientific  world  that  will  now 
occupy    our    attention.       In    accordance    with    the    last 


THE  REAL  AND  THE  CONCRETE  275 

chapter  we  are  takfng  a  larger  view  in  which  the  cyclical 
schemes  of  physics  are  embraced  with  much  besides. 
But  before  venturing  on  this  more  risky  ground  I  have 
to  emphasise  one  conclusion  which  is  definitely  scien- 
tific. The  modern  scientific  theories  have  broken  away 
from  the  common  standpoint  which  identifies  the  real 
with  the  concrete.  I  think  we  might  go  so  far  as  to  say 
that  time  is  more  typical  of  physical  reality  than  matter, 
because  it  is  freer  from  those  metaphysical  associations 
which  physics  disallows.  It  would  not  be  fair,  being 
given  an  inch,  to  take  an  ell,  and  say  that  having  gone 
so  far  physics  may  as  well  admit  at  once  that  reality  is 
spiritual.  We  must  go  more  warily.  But  in  approaching 
such  questions  we  are  no  longer  tempted  to  take  up  the 
attitude  that  everything  which  lacks  concreteness  is 
thereby  self-condemned. 

The  cleavage  between  the  scientific  and  the  extra- 
scientific  domain  of  experience  is,  I  believe,  not  a 
cleavage  between  the  concrete  and  the  transcendental 
but  between  the  metrical  and  the  non-metrical.  I  am 
at  one  with  the  materialist  in  feeling  a  repugnance 
towards  any  kind  of  pseudo-science  of  the  extra- 
scientific  territory.  Science  is  not  to  be  condemned  as 
narrow  because  it  refuses  to  deal  with  elements  of 
experience  which  are  unadapted  to  its  own  highly 
organised  method ;  nor  can  it  be  blamed  for  looking  super- 
ciliously on  the  comparative  disorganisation  of  our  knowl- 
edge and  methods  of  reasoning  about  the  non-metrical 
part  of  experience.  But  I  think  we  have  not  been  guilty 
of  pseudo-science  in  our  attempt  to  show  in  the  last  two 
chapters  how  it  comes  about  that  within  the  whole 
domain  of  experience  a  selected  portion  is  capable  of 
that  exact  metrical  representation  which  is  requisite  for 
development  by  the  scientific  method. 


276  REALITY 

Mind-Stuff.  I  will  try  to  be  as  definite  as  I  can  as  to  the 
glimpse  of  reality  which  we  seem  to  have  reached.  Only 
I  am  well  aware  that  in  committing  myself  to  details 
I  shall  probably  blunder.  Even  if  the  right  view  has 
here  been  taken  of  the  philosophical  trend  of  modern 
science,  it  is  premature  to  suggest  a  cut-and-dried 
scheme  of  the  nature  of  things.  If  the  criticism  is  made 
that  certain  aspects  are  touched  on  which  come  more 
within  the  province  of  the  expert  psychologist,  I  must 
admit  its  pertinence.  The  recent  tendencies  of  science 
do,  I  believe,  take  us  to  an  eminence  from  which  we 
can  look  down  into  the  deep  waters  of  philosophy;  and 
if  I  rashly  plunge  into  them,,  it  is  not  because  I  have 
confidence  in  my  powers  of  swimming,  but  to  try  to 
show  that  the  water  is  really  deep. 

To  put  the  conclusion  crudely — the  stuff  of  the  world 
is  mind-stuff.  As  is  often  the  way  with  crude  statements, 
I  shall  have  to  explain  that  by  "mind"  I  do  not  here 
exactly  mean  mind  and  by  "stuff"  I  do  not  at  all  mean 
stuff.  Still  this  is  about  as  near  as  we  can  get  to  the  idea 
in  a  simple  phrase.  The  mind-stuff  of  the  world  is,  of 
course,  something  more  general  than  our  individual 
conscious  minds;  but  we  may  think  of  its  nature  as  not 
altogether  foreign  to  the  feelings  in  our  consciousness. 
The  realistic  matter  and  fields  of  force  of  former 
physical  theory  are  altogether  irrelevant — except  in  so 
far  as  the  mind-stuff  has  itself  spun  these  imaginings. 
The  symbolic  matter  and  fields  of  force  of  present-day 
theory  are  more  relevant,  but  they  bear  to  it  the  same 
relation  that  the  bursar's  accounts  bear  to  the  activity 
of  the  college.  Having  granted  this,  the  mental  activity 
of  the  part  of  the  world  constituting  ourselves  occasions 
no  surprise;  it  is  known  to  us  by  direct  self-knowledge, 
and  we  do  not  explain  it  away  as  something  other  than 


MIND-STUFF  277 

we  know  it  to  be — or,  rather,  it  knows  itself  to  be.  It 
is  the  physical  aspects  of  the  world  that  we  have  to 
explain,  presumably  by  some  such  method  as  that  set 
forth  in  our  discussion  on  world-building.  Our  bodies 
are  more  mysterious  than  our  minds — at  least  they 
would  be,  only  that  we  can  set  the  mystery  on  one  side 
by  the  device  of  the  cyclic  scheme  of  physics,  which 
enables  us  to  study  their  phenomenal  behaviour  without 
ever  coming  to  grips  with  the  underlying  mystery. 

The  mind-stuff  is  not  spread  in  space  and  time;  these 
are  part  of  the  cyclic  scheme  ultimately  derived  out  of 
it.  But  we  must  presume  that  in  some  other  way  or 
aspect  it  can  be  differentiated  into  parts.  Only  here  and 
there  does  it  rise  to  the  level  of  consciousness,  but  from 
such  islands  proceeds  all  knowledge.  Besides  the  direct 
knowledge  contained  in  each  self-knowing  unit,  there 
is  inferential  knowledge.  The  latter  includes  our  know- 
ledge of  the  physical  world.  It  is  necessary  to  keep 
reminding  ourselves  that  all  knowledge  of  our  environ- 
ment from  which  the  world  of  physics  is  constructed, 
has  entered  in  the  form  of  messages  transmitted  along 
the  nerves  to  the  seat  of  consciousness.  Obviously  the 
messages  travel  in  code.  When  messages  relating  to  a 
table  are  travelling  in  the  nerves,  the  nerve-disturbance 
does  not  in  the  least  resemble  either  the  external  table 
that  originates  the  mental  impression  or  the  conception 
of  the  table  that  arises  in  consciousness.*  In  the  central 
clearing  station  the  incoming  messages  are  sorted  and 
decoded,   partly   by   instinctive    image-building   inherited 

*I  mean,  resemble  in  intrinsic  nature.  It  is  true  (as  Bertrand  Russell 
has  emphasised)  that  the  symbolic  description  of  structure  will  be  iden- 
tical for  thet  table  in  the  external  world  and  for  the  conception  of  the 
table  in  consciousness  if  the  conception  is  scientifically  correct.  If  the 
physicist  does  not  attempt  to  penetrate  beneath  the  structure  he  is  in- 
different as  to  which  of  the  two  we  imagine  ourselves  to  be  discussing. 


278  REALITY 

from  the  experience  of  our  ancestors,  partly  by  scientific 
comparison  and  reasoning.  By  this  very  indirect  and 
hypothetical  inference  all  our  supposed  acquaintance 
with  and  our  theories  of  a  world  outside  us  have  been 
built  up.  We  are  acquainted  with  an  external  world 
because  its  fibres  run  into  our  consciousness;  it  is  only 
our  own  ends  of  the  fibres  that  we  actually  know;  from 
those  ends  we  more  or  less  successfully  reconstruct  the 
rest,  as  a  palaeontologist  reconstructs  an  extinct  monster 
from  its  footprint. 

The  mind-stuff  is  the  aggregation  of  relations  and 
relata  which  form  the  building  material  for  the  physical 
world.  Our  account  of  the  building  process  shows, 
however,  that  much  that  is  implied  in  the  relations  is 
dropped  as  unserviceable  for  the  required  building. 
Our  view  is  practically  that  urged  in  1875  by  W.  K. 
Clifford— 

"The  succession  of  feelings  which  constitutes  a  man's 
consciousness  is  the  reality  which  produces  in  our  minds 
the  perception  of  the  motions  of  his  brain." 

That  is  to  say,  that  which  the  man  himself  knows  as 
a  succession  of  feelings  is  the  reality  which  when  probed 
by  the  appliances  of  an  outside  investigator  affects  their 
readings  in  such  a  way  that  it  is  identified  as  a  configura- 
tion of  brain-matter.    Again  Bertrand  Russell  writes — * 

What  the  physiologist  sees  when  he  examines  a  brain  is  in  the 
physiologist,  not  in  the  brain  he  is  examining.  What  is  in  the 
brain  by  the  time  the  physiologist  examines  it  if  it  is  dead,  I  do 
not  profess  to  know;  but  while  its  owner  was  alive,  part,  at  least, 
of  the  contents  of  his  brain  consisted  of  his  percepts,  thoughts, 
and  feelings.  Since  his  brain  also  consisted  of  electrons,  we  are 
compelled  to  conclude  that  an  electron  is  a  grouping  of  events, 

*  Analysis  of  Matter,  p.  320. 


MIND-STUFF  279 

and  that  if  the  electron  is  in  a  human  brain,  some  of  the  events 
composing  it  are  likely  to  be  some  of  the  "mental  states"  of  the 
man  to  whom  the  brain  belongs.  Or,  at  any  rate,  they  are  likely 
to  be  parts  of  such  "mental  states" — for  it  must  not  be  assumed 
that  part  of  a  mental  state  must  be  a  mental  state.  I  do  not  wish 
to  discuss  what  is  meant  by  a  "mental  state";  the  main  point  for 
us  is  that  the  term  must  include  percepts.  Thus  a  percept  is  an 
event  or  a  group  of  events,  each  of  which  belongs  to  one  or  more 
of  the  groups  constituting  the  electrons  in  the  brain.  This, 
I  think,  is  the  most  concrete  statement  that  can  be  made  about 
electrons;  everything  else  that  can  be  said  is  more  or  less  abstract 
and  mathematical. 

I  quote  this  partly  for  the  sake  of  the  remark  that  it 
must  not  be  assumed  that  part  of  a  mental  state  must 
necessarily  be  a  mental  state.  We  can  no  doubt  analyse 
the  content  of  consciousness  during  a  short  interval  of 
time  into  more  or  less  elementary  constituent  feelings; 
but  it  is  not  suggested  that  this  psychological  analysis 
will  reveal  the  elements  out  of  whose  measure-numbers 
the  atoms  or  electrons  are  built.  The  brain-matter  is  a 
partial  aspect  of  the  whole  mental  state;  but  the  analysis 
of  the  brain-matter  by  physical  investigation  does  not 
run  at  all  parallel  with  the  analysis  of  the  mental  state 
by  psychological  investigation.  I  assume  that  Russell 
meant  to  warn  us  that,  in  speaking  of  part  of  a  mental 
state,  he  was  not  limiting  himself  to  parts  that  would 
be  recognised  as  such  psychologically,  and  he  was  ad- 
mitting a  more  abstract  kind  of  dissection. 

This  might  give  rise  to  some  difficulty  if  we  were 
postulating  complete  identity  of  mind-stuff  with  con- 
sciousness. But  we  know  that  in  the  mind  there  are 
memories  not  in  consciousness  at  the  moment  but 
capable  of  being  summoned  into  consciousness.  We 
are  vaguely  aware  that  things  we  cannot  recall  are  lying 
somewhere  about  and  may  come  into  the  mind  at  any 


280  REALITY 

moment.  Consciousness  is  not  sharply  defined,  but 
fades  into  subconsciousness;  and  beyond  that  we  must 
postulate  something  indefinite  but  yet  continuous  with 
our  mental  nature.  This  I  take  to  be  the  world-stuff. 
We  liken  it  to  our  conscious  feelings  because,  now  that 
we  are  convinced  of  the  formal  and  symbolic  character  of 
the  entities  of  physics,  there  is  nothing  else  to  liken  it  to. 

It  is  sometimes  urged  that  the  basal  stuff  of  the  world 
should  be  called  "neutral  stuff"  rather  than  "mind- 
stuff",  since  it  is  to  be  such  that  both  mind  and  matter 
originate  from  it.  If  this  is  intended  to  emphasise  that 
only  limited  islands  of  it  constitute  actual  minds,  and 
that  even  in  these  islands  that  which  is  known  mentally 
is  not  equivalent  to  a  complete  inventory  of  all  that  may 
be  there,  I  agree.  In  fact  I  should  suppose  that  the 
self-knowledge  of  consciousness  is  mainly  or  wholly  a 
knowledge  which  eludes  the  inventory  method  of  de- 
scription. The  term  "mind-stuff"  might  well  be  amended; 
but  neutral  stuff  seems  to  be  the  wrong  kind  of  amend- 
ment. It  implies  that  we  have  two  avenues  of  approach 
to  an  understanding  of  its  nature.  We  have  only  one 
approach,  namely,  through  our  direct  knowledge  of 
mind.  The  supposed  approach  through  the  physical 
world  leads  only  into  the  cycle  of  physics,  where  we  run 
round  and  round  like  a  kitten  chasing  its  tail  and  never 
reach  the  world-stuff  at  all. 

I  assume  that  we  have  left  the  illusion  of  substance 
so  far  behind  that  the  word  "stuff"  will  not  cause  any 
misapprehension.  I  certainly  do  not  intend  to  materialise 
or  substantialise  mind.  Mind  is — but  you  know  what 
mind  is  like,  so  why  should  I  say  more  about  its  nature? 
The  word  "stuff"  has  reference  to  the  function  it  has 
to  perform  as  a  basis  of  world-building  and  does  not 
imply  any  modified  view  of  its  nature. 


MIND-STUFF  281 

It  is  difficult  for  the  matter-of-fact  physicist  to  accept 
the  view  that  the  substratum  of  everything  is  of  mental 
character.  But  no  one  can  deny  that  mind  is  the  first 
and  most  direct  thing  in  our  experience,  and  all  else  is 
remote  inference — inference  either  intuitive  or  deli- 
berate. Probably  it  would  never  have  occurred  to  us 
(as  a  serious  hypothesis)  that  the  world  could  be  based 
on  anything  else,  had  we  not  been  under  the  impression 
that  there  was  a  rival  stuff  with  a  more  comfortable  kind 
of  "concrete"  reality — something  too  inert  and  stupid 
to  be  capable  of  forging  an  illusion.  The  rival  turns 
out  to  be  a  schedule  of  pointer  readings;  and  though  a 
world  of  symbolic  character  can  well  be  constructed  from 
it,  this  is  a  mere  shelving  of  the  inquiry  into  the  nature 
of  the  world  of  experience. 

This  view  of  the  relation  of  the  material  to  the 
spiritual  world  perhaps  relieves  to  some  extent  a  tension 
between  science  and  religion.  Physical  science  has 
seemed  to  occupy  a  domain  of  reality  which  is  self- 
sufficient,  pursuing  its  course  independently  of  and 
indifferent  to  that  which  a  voice  within  us  asserts  to  be 
a  higher  reality.  We  are  jealous  of  such  independence. 
We  are  uneasy  that  there  should  be  an  apparently  self- 
contained  world  in  which  God  becomes  an  unnecessary 
hypothesis.  We  acknowledge  that  the  ways  of  God  are 
inscrutable;  but  is  there  not  still  in  the  religious  mind 
something  of  that  feeling  of  the  prophets  of  old,  who 
called  on  God  to  assert  his  kingship  and  by  sign  or 
miracle  proclaim  that  the  forces  of  Nature  are  subject 
to  his  command?  And  yet  if  the  scientist  were  to  repent 
and  admit  that  it  was  necessary  to  include  among 
the  agents  controlling  the  stars  and  the  electrons  an  omni- 
present spirit  to  whom  we  trace  the  sacred  things  of  con- 
sciousness, would  there  not  be  even  graver  apprehension  ? 


282  REALITY 

We  should  suspect  an  intention  to  reduce  God  to  a  system 
of  differential  equations,  like  the  other  agents  which  at 
various  times  have  been  introduced  to  restore  order  in  the 
physical  scheme.  That  fiasco  at  any  rate  is  avoided.  For 
the  sphere  of  the  differential  equations  of  physics  is  the 
metrical  cyclic  scheme  extracted  out  of  the  broader 
reality.  However  much  the  ramifications  of  the  cycles 
may  be  extended  by  further  scientific  discovery,  they 
cannot  from  their  very  nature  trench  on  the  background 
in  which  they  have  their  being — their  actuality.  It  is 
in  this  background  that  our  own  mental  consciousness  lies; 
and  here,  if  anywhere,  we  may  find  a  Power  greater  than 
but  akin  to  consciousness.  It  is  not  possible  for  the  con- 
trolling laws  of  the  spiritual  substratum,  which  in  so  far 
as  it  is  known  to  us  in  consciousness  is  essentially  non- 
metrical,  to  be  analogous  to  the  differential  and  other 
mathematical  equations  of  physics  which  are  meaningless 
unless  they  are  fed  with  metrical  quantities.  So  that  the 
crudest  anthropomorphic  image  of  a  spiritual  deity  can 
scarcely  be  so  wide  of  the  truth  as  one  conceived  in  terms 
of  metrical  equations. 

The  Definition  of  Reality.  It  is  time  we  came  to  grips 
with  the  loose  terms  Reality  and  Existence,  which  we 
have  been  using  without  any  inquiry  into  what  they  are 
meant  to  convey.  I  am  afraid  of  this  word  Reality,  not 
connoting  an  ordinarily  definable  characteristic  of  the 
things  it  is  applied  to  but  used  as  though  it  were  some 
kind  of  celestial  halo.  I  very  much  doubt  if  any  one  of 
us  has  the  faintest  idea  of  what  is  meant  by  the  reality 
or  existence  of  anything  but  our  own  Egos.  That  is  a 
bold  statement,  which  I  must  guard  against  misinter- 
pretation. It  is,  of  course,  possible  to  obtain  consistent 
use   of  the  word   "reality"   by  adopting  a   conventional 


THE  DEFINITION  OF  REALITY  283 

definition.  My  own  practice  would  probably  be  covered 
by  the  definition  that  a  thing  may  be  said  to  be  real  if 
it  is  the  goal  of  a  type  of  inquiry  to  which  I  personally 
attach  importance.  But  if  I  insist  on  no  more  than  this 
I  am  whittling  down  the  significance  that  is  generally 
assumed.  In  physics  we  can  give  a  cold  scientific 
definition  of  reality  which  is  free  from  all  sentimental 
mystification.  But  this  is  not  quite  fair  play,  because  the 
word  "reality"  is  generally  used  with  the  intention  of 
evoking  sentiment.  It  is  a  grand  word  for  a  peroration. 
"The  right  honourable  speaker  went  on  to  declare  that 
the  concord  and  amity  for  which  he  had  unceasingly 
striven  had  now  become  a  reality  (loud  cheers). "  The 
conception  which  it  is  so  troublesome  to  apprehend  is 
not  "reality"  but  "reality  (loud  cheers)". 

Let  us  first  examine  the  definition  according  to  the 
purely  scientific  usage  of  the  word,  although  it  will  not 
take  us  far  enough.  The  only  subject  presented  to  me 
for  study  is  the  content  of  my  consciousness.  You  are 
able  to  communicate  to  me  part  of  the  content  of  your 
consciousness  which  thereby  becomes  accessible  in  my 
own.  For  reasons  which  are  generally  admitted,  though 
I  should  not  like  to  have  to  prove  that  they  are  conclusive, 
I  grant  your  consciousness  equal  status  with  my  own; 
and  I  use  this  second-hand  part  of  my  consciousness  to 
"put  myself  in  your  place".  Accordingly  my  subject  of 
study  becomes  differentiated  into  the  contents  of  many 
consciousnesses,  each  content  constituting  a  view-point. 
There  then  arises  the  problem  of  combining  the  view- 
points, and  it  is  through  this  that  the  external  world  of 
physics  arises.  Much  that  is  in  any  one  consciousness 
is  individual,  much  is  apparently  alterable  by  volition; 
but  there  is  a  stable  element  which  is  common  to  other' 
consciousnesses.      That   common    element   we    desire    to 


284  REALITY 

study,  to  describe  as  fully  and  accurately  as  possible, 
and  to  discover  the  laws  by  which  it  combines  now  with 
one  view-point,  now  with  another.  This  common  ele- 
ment cannot  be  placed  in  one  man's  consciousness 
rather  than  in  another's;  it  must  be  in  neutral  ground — 
an  external  world. 

It  is  true  that  I  have  a  strong  impression  of  an  external 
world  apart  from  any  communication  with  other  con- 
scious beings.  But  apart  from  such  communication 
I  should  have  no  reason  to  trust  the  impression.  Most 
of  our  common  impressions  of  substance,  world-wide 
instants,  and  so  on,  have  turned  out  to  be  illusory,  and 
the  externality  of  the  world  might  be  equally  untrust- 
worthy. The  impression  of  externality  is  equally  strong 
in  the  world  that  comes  to  me  in  dreams;  the  dream- 
world is  less  rational,  but  that  might  be  used  as  an  argu- 
ment in  favour  of  its  externality  as  showing  its  dissocia- 
tion from  the  internal  faculty  of  reason.  So  long  as  we 
have  to  deal  with  one  consciousness  alone,  the  hypothesis 
that  there  is  an  external  world  responsible  for  part  of 
what  appears  in  it  is  an  idle  one.  All  that  can  be  asserted 
of  this  external  world  is  a  mere  duplication  of  the  know- 
ledge that  can  be  much  more  confidently  asserted  of  the 
world  appearing  in  the  consciousness.  The  hypothesis 
only  becomes  useful  when  it  is  the  means  of  bringing 
together  the  worlds  of  many  consciousnesses  occupying 
different  view-points. 

The  external  world  of  physics  is  thus  a  symposium 
of  the  worlds  presented  to  different  view-points.  There 
is  general  agreement  as  to  the  principles  on  which  the 
symposium  should  be  formed.  Statements  made  about 
this  external  world,  if  they  are  unambiguous,  must  be 
either  true  or  false.  This  has  often  been  denied  by 
philosophers.      It  is  quite  commonly  said  that  scientific 


THE  DEFINITION  OF  REALITY  285 

theories  about  the  world  are  neither  true  nor  false  but 
merely  convenient  or  inconvenient.  A  favourite  phrase 
is  that  the  gauge  of  value  of  a  scientific  theory  is  that  it 
economises  thought.  Certainly  a  simple  statement  is 
preferable  to  a  circumlocutory  one;  and  as  regards  any 
current  scientific  theory,  it  is  much  easier  to  show  that 
it  is  convenient  or  that  it  economises  thought  than  that 
it  is  true.  But  whatever  lower  standards  we  may  apply 
in  practice  we  need  not  give  up  our  ideals;  and  so  long 
as  there  is  a  distinction  between  true  and  false  theories 
our  aim  must  be  to  eliminate  the  false.  For  my  part 
I  hold  that  the  continual  advance  of  science  is  not  a 
mere  utilitarian  progress;  it  is  progress  towards  ever 
purer  truth.  Only  let  it  be  understood  that  the  truth 
we  seek  in  science  is  the  truth  about  an  external  world 
propounded  as  the  theme  of  study,  and  is  not  bound  up 
with  any  opinion  as  to  the  status  of  that  world — whether 
or  not  it  wears  the  halo  of  reality,  whether  or  not  it  is 
deserving  of  "loud  cheers". 

Assuming  that  the  symposium  has  been  correctly 
carried  out,  the  external  world  and  all  that  appears  in  it 
are  called  real  without  further  ado.  When  we  (scientists) 
assert  of  anything  in  the  external  world  that  it  is  real 
and  that  it  exists,  we  are  expressing  our  belief  that  the 
rules  of  the  symposium  have  been  correctly  applied — 
that  it  is  not  a  false  concept  introduced  by  an  error  in 
the  process  of  synthesis,  or  a  iiallucination  belonging  to 
only  one  individual  consciousness,  or  an  incomplete 
representation  which  embraces  certain  view-points  but 
conflicts  with  others.  We  refuse  to  contemplate  the 
awful  contingency  that  the  external  world,  after  all  our 
care  in  arriving  at  it,  might  be  disqualified  by  failing 
to  exist;  because  we  have  no  idea  what  the  supposed 
qualification    would    consist    in,    nor    in    what    way    the 


286  REALITY 

prestige  of  the  world  would  be  enhanced  if  it  passed 
the  implied  test.  The  external  world  is  the  world  that 
confronts  that  experience  which  we  have  in  common, 
and  for  us  no  other  world  could  fill  the  same  role,  no 
matter  how  high  honours  it  might  take  in  the  qualifying 
examination. 

This  domestic  definition  of  existence  for  scientific 
purposes  follows  the  principle  now  adopted  for  all  other 
definitions  in  science,  namely,  that  a  thing  must  be 
defined  according  to  the  way  in  which  it  is  in  practice 
recognised  and  not  according  to  some  ulterior  signi- 
ficance that  we  imagine  it  to  possess.  Just  as  matter 
must  shed  its  conception  of  substantiality,  so  existence 
must  shed  its  halo,  before  we  can  admit  it  into  physical 
science.  But  clearly  if  we  are  to  assert  or  to  question 
the  existence  of  anything  not  comprised  in  the  external 
world  of  physics,  we  must  look  beyond  the  physical 
definition.  The  mere  questioning  of  the  reality  of  the 
physical  world  implies  some  higher  censorship  than  the 
scientific  method  itself  can  supply. 

The  external  world  of  physics  has  been  formulated 
as  an  answer  to  a  particular  problem  encountered  in 
human  experience.  Officially  the  scientist  regards  it  as 
a  problem  which  he  just  happened  across,  as  he  might 
take  up  a  cross-word  problem  encountered  in  a  news- 
paper. His  sole  business  is  to  see  that  the  problem  is 
correctly  solved.  But  questions  may  be  raised  about  a 
problem  which  play  no  part  and  need  not  be  considered 
in  connection  with  the  solving  of  the  problem.  The 
extraneous  question  naturally  raised  about  the  problem 
of  the  external  world  is  whether  there  is  some  higher 
justification  for  embarking  on  this  world-solving  com- 
petition rather  than  on  other  problems  which  our 
experience    might    suggest    to    us.      Just    what    kind    of 


THE  DEFINITION  OF  REALITY  287 

justification  the  scientist  would  claim  for  his  quest  is  not 
very  clear,  because  it  is  not  within  the  province  of  science 
to  formulate  such  a  claim.  But  certainly  he  makes 
claims  which  do  not  rest  on  the  aesthetic  perfection  of 
the  solution  or  on  material  benefits  derived  from  scien- 
tific research.  He  would  not  allow  his  subject  to  be 
shoved  aside  in  a  symposium  on  truth.  We  can  scarcely 
say  anything  more  definite  than  that  science  claims  a 
"halo"  for  its  world. 

If  we  are  to  find  for  the  atoms  and  electrons  of  the 
external  world  not  merely  a  conventional  reality  but 
"reality  (loud  cheers)"  we  must  look  not  to  the  end  but 
to  the  beginning  of  the  quest.  It  is  at  the  beginning  that 
we  must  find  that  sanction  which  raises  these  entities 
above  the  mere  products  of  an  arbitrary  mental  exercise. 
This  involves  some  kind  of  assessment  of  the  impulse 
which  sets  us  forth  on  the  voyage  of  discovery.  How 
can  we  make  such  assessment?  Not  by  any  reasoning 
that  I  know  of.  Reasoning  would  only  tell  us  that  the 
impulse  might  be  judged  by  the  success  of  the  adventure 
— whether  it  leads  in  the  end  to  things  which  really 
exist  and  wear  the  halo  in  their  own  right;  it  takes  us 
to  and  fro  like  a  shuttle  along  the  chain  of  inference  in 
vain  search  for  the  elusive  halo.  But,  legitimately  or  not, 
the  mind  is  confident  that  it  can  distinguish  certain 
quests  as  sanctioned  by  indisputable  authority.  We 
may  put  it  in  different  ways  ;-  the  impulse  to  this  quest 
is  part  of  our  very  nature;  it  is  the  expression  of  a 
purpose  which  has  possession  of  us.  Is  this  precisely 
what  we  meant  when  we  sought  to  affirm  the  reality  of 
the  external  world?  It  goes  some  way  towards  giving 
it  a  meaning  but  is  scarcely  the  full  equivalent.  I  doubt 
if  we  really  satisfy  the  conceptions  behind  that  demand 
unless   we   make   the    bolder   hypothesis    that   the    quest 


288  REALITY 

and  all  that  is  reached  by  it  are  of  worth  in  the  eyes  of 
an  Absolute  Valuer. 

Whatever  justification  at  the  source  we  accept  to 
vindicate  the  reality  of  the  external  world,  it  can  scarcely 
fail  to  admit  on  the  same  footing  much  that  is  outside 
physical  science.  Although  no  long  chains  of  regularised 
inference  depend  from  them  we  recognise  that  other 
fibres  of  our  being  extend  in  directions  away  from 
sense-impressions.  I  am  not  greatly  concerned  to  borrow 
words  like  "existence"  and  "reality"  to  crown  these 
other  departments  of  the  soul's  interest.  I  would  rather 
put  it  that  any  raising  of  the  question  of  reality  in  its 
transcendental  sense  (whether  the  question  emanates 
from  the  world  of  physics  or  not)  leads  us  to  a  perspective 
from  which  we  see  man  not  as  a  bundle  of  sensory 
impressions,  but  conscious  of  purpose  and  responsi- 
bilities to  which  the  external  world  is  subordinate. 

From  this  perspective  we  recognise  a  spiritual  world 
alongside  the  physical  world.  Experience — that  is  to 
say,  the  self  cum  environment — comprises  more  than 
can  be  embraced  in  the  physical  world,  restricted  as  it 
is  to  a  complex  of  metrical  symbols.  The  physical  world 
is,  we  have  seen,  the  answer  to  one  definite  and  urgent 
problem  arising  in  a  survey  of  experience;  and  no  other 
problem  has  been  followed  up  with  anything  like  the 
same  precision  and  elaboration.  Progress  towards  an 
understanding  of  the  non-sensory  constituents  of  our 
nature  is  not  likely  to  follow  similar  lines,  and  indeed 
is  not  animated  by  the  same  aims.  If  it  is  felt  that  this 
difference  is  so  wide  that  the  phrase  spiritual  world  is  a 
misleading  analogy,  I  will  not  insist  on  the  term.  All 
I  would  claim  is  that  those  who  in  the  search  for  truth 
start  from  consciousness  as  a  seat  of  self-knowledge  with 
interests  and  responsibilities  not  confined  to  the  material 


PHYSICAL  ILLUSTRATIONS  289 

plane,  are  just  as  much  facing  the  hard  facts  of  experi- 
ence as  those  who  start  from  consciousness  as  a  device 
for  reading  the  indications  of  spectroscopes  and  micro- 
meters. 

Physical  Illustrations.  If  the  reader  is  unconvinced  that 
there  can  be  anything  indefinite  in  the  question  whether 
a  thing  exists  or  not,  let  him  glance  at  the  following 
problem.  Consider  a  distribution  of  matter  in  Einstein's 
spherical  "finite  but  unbounded"  space.  Suppose  that 
the  matter  is  so  arranged  that  every  particle  has  an 
exactly  similar  particle  at  its  antipodes.  (There  is  some 
reason  to  believe  that  the  matter  would  necessarily  have 
this  arrangement  in  consequence  of  the  law  of  gravita- 
tion; but  this  is  not  certain.)  Each  group  of  particles 
will  therefore  be  exactly  like  the  antipodal  group  not 
only  in  its  structure  and  configuration  but  in  its  entire 
surroundings;  the  two  groups  will  in  fact  be  indis- 
tinguishable by  any  possible  experimental  test.  Starting 
on  a  journey  round  the  spherical  world  we  come  across 
a  group  A,  and  then  after  going  half  round  we  come  to 
an  exactly  similar  group  A'  indistinguishable  by  any 
test;  another  half  circle  again  brings  us  to  an  exactly 
similar  group,  which,  however,  we  decide  is  the  original 
group  A.  Now  let  us  ponder  a  little.  We  realise  that 
in  any  case  by  going  on  far  enough  we  come  back  to  the 
same  group.  Why  do  we  not  accept  the  obvious  con- 
clusion that  this  happened  when  we  reached  A';  every- 
thing was  exactly  as  though  we  had  reached  the  starting- 
point  again?  We  have  encountered  a  succession  of 
precisely  similar  phenomena  but  for  some  arbitrary 
reason  have  decided  that  only  the  alternate  ones  are 
really  the  same.  There  is  no  difficulty  in  identifying  all 
of  them;  in  that  case  the  space  is  "elliptical"  instead  of 


29Q  REALITY 

"spherical".  But  which  is  the  real  truth?  Disregard 
the  fact  that  I  introduced  A  and  A'  to  you  as  though 
they  were  not  the  same  particles,  because  that  begs  the 
question;  imagine  that  you  have  actually  had  this 
adventure  in  a  world  you  had  not  been  told  about.  You 
cannot  find  out  the  answer.  Can  you  conceive  what  the 
question  means  ?  I  cannot.  All  that  turns  on  the  answer 
is  whether  we  shall  provide  two  separate  haloes  for  A 
and  A'  or  whether  one  will  suffice. 

Descriptions  of  the  phenomena  of  atomic  physics 
have  an  extraordinary  vividness.  We  see  the  atoms  with 
their  girdles  of  circulating  electrons  darting  hither  and 
thither,  colliding  and  rebounding.  Free  electrons  torn 
from  the  girdles  hurry  away  a  hundred  times  faster, 
curving  sharply  round  the  atoms  with  side  slips  and 
hairbreadth  escapes.  The  truants  are  caught  and 
attached  to  the  girdles  and  the  escaping  energy  shakes 
the  aether  into  vibration.  X-rays  impinge  on  the  atoms 
and  toss  the  electrons  into  higher  orbits.  We  see  these 
electrons  falling  back  again,  sometimes  by  steps,  some- 
times with  a  rush,  caught  in  a  cul-de-sac  of  metasta- 
bility,  hesitating  before  "forbidden  passages".  Behind 
it  all  the  quantum  h  regulates  each  change  with  mathe- 
matical precision.  This  is  the  sort  of  picture  that  appeals 
to  our  understanding — no  insubstantial  pageant  to  fade 
like  a  dream. 

The  spectacle  is  so  fascinating  that  we  have  perhaps 
forgotten  that  there  was  a  time  when  we  wanted  to  be 
told  what  an  electron  is.  The  question  was  never 
answered.  No  familiar  conceptions  can  be  woven  round 
the  electron;  it  belongs  to  the  waiting  list.  Similarly 
the  description  of  the  processes  must  be  taken  with  a 
grain  of  salt.  The  tossing  up  of  the  electron  is  a  con- 
ventional way  of  depicting  a  particular  change  of  state 


PHYSICAL  ILLUSTRATIONS  291 

of  the  atom  which  cannot  really  be  associated  with 
movements  in  space  as  macroscopically  conceived. 
Something  unknown  is  doing  we  don't  know  what — that  is 
what  our  theory  amounts  to.  It  does  not  sound  a  par- 
ticularly illuminating  theory.  I  have  read  something 
like  it  elsewhere — 

The  slithy  toves 
Did  gyre   and   gimble   in   the   wabe. 

There  is  the  same  suggestion  of  activity.  There  is  the 
same  indefiniteness  as  to  the  nature  of  the  activity  and 
of  what  it  is  that  is  acting.  And  yet  from  so  unpromising 
a  beginning  we  really  do  get  somewhere.  We  bring 
into  order  a  host  of  apparently  unrelated  phenomena; 
we  make  predictions,  and  our  predictions  come  off. 
The  reason — the  sole  reason — for  this  progress  is  that 
our  description  is  not  limited  to  unknown  agents 
executing  unknown  activities,  but  numbers  are  scattered 
freely  in  the  description.  To  contemplate  electrons 
circulating  in  the  atom  carries  us  no  further;  but  by 
contemplating  eight  circulating  electrons  in  one  atom 
and  seven  circulating  electrons  in  another  we  begin  to 
realise  the  difference  between  oxygen  and  nitrogen. 
Eight  slithy  toves  gyre  and  gimble  in  the  oxygen  wabe; 
seven  in  nitrogen.  By  admitting  a  few  numbers  even 
"Jabberwocky"  may  become  scientific.  We  can  now 
venture  on  a  prediction;  if  one  of  its  toves  escapes, 
oxygen  will  be  masquerading  in  a  garb  properly  be- 
longing to  nitrogen.  In  the  stars  and  nebulae  we  do 
find  such  wolves  in  sheep's  clothing  which  might 
otherwise  have  startled  us.  It  would  not  be  a  bad 
reminder  of  the  essential  unknownness  of  the  funda- 
mental entities  of  physics  to  translate  it  into  "Jabber- 
wocky"; provided  all  numbers — all   metrical   attributes 


292  REALITY 

— are  unchanged,  it  does  not  suffer  in  the  least.  Out 
of  the  numbers  proceeds  that  harmony  of  natural  law 
which  it  is  the  aim  of  science  to  disclose.  We  can  grasp 
the  tune  but  not  the  player.  Trinculo  might  have  been 
referring  to  modern  physics  in  the  words,  "This  is  the 
tune  of  our  catch,  played  by  the  picture  of  Nobody". 


Chapter  XIV 

CAUSATION 

In  the  old  conflict  between  freewill  and  predestination 
it  has  seemed  hitherto  that  physics  comes  down  heavily 
on  the  side  of  predestination.  Without  making  ex- 
travagant claims  for  the  scope  of  natural  law,  its  moral 
sympathy  has  been  with  the  view  that  whatever  the 
future  may  bring  forth  is  already  foretold  in  the  con- 
figurations of  the  past — 

Yea,  the  first  Morning  of  Creation  wrote 

What   the   Last    Dawn   of   Reckoning   shall   read. 

I  am  not  so  rash  as  to  invade  Scotland  with  a  solution 
of  a  problem  which  has  rent  her  from  the  synod  to  the 
cottage.  Like  most  other  people,  I  suppose,  I  think  it 
incredible  that  the  wider  scheme  of  Nature  which 
includes  life  and  consciousness  can  be  completely 
predetermined;  yet  I  have  not  been  able  to  form  a 
satisfactory  conception  of  any  kind  of  law  or  causal 
sequence  which  shall  be  other  than  deterministic.  It 
seems  contrary  to  our  feeling  of  the  dignity  of  the  mind 
to  suppose  that  it  merely  registers  a  dictated  sequence 
of  thoughts  and  emotions;  but  it  seems  equally  con- 
trary to  its  dignity  to  put  it  at  the  mercy  of  impulses 
with  no  causal  antecedents.  I  shall  not  deal  with  this 
dilemma.  Here  I  have  to  set  forth  the  position  of 
physical  science  on  this  matter  so  far  as  it  comes  into 
her  territory.  It  does  come  into  her  territory,  because 
that  which  we  call  human  will  cannot  be  entirely 
dissociated  from  the  consequent  motions  of  the  muscles 
and  disturbance  of  the  material  world.     On  the  scientific 

293 


294  CAUSATION 

side  a  new  situation  has  arisen.  It  is  a  consequence  of 
the  advent  of  the  quantum  theory  that  physics  is  no 
longer  pledged  to  a  scheme  of  deterministic  law.  Deter- 
minism has  dropped  out  altogether  in  the  latest  for- 
mulations of  theoretical  physics  and  it  is  at  least  open 
to  doubt  whether  it  will  ever  be  brought  back. 

The  foregoing  paragraph  is  from  the  manuscript  of 
the  original  lecture  delivered  in  Edinburgh.  The  attitude 
of  physics  at  that  time  was  one  of  indifference  to  deter- 
minism. If  there  existed  a  scheme  of  strictly  causal  law 
at  the  base  of  phenomena  the  search  for  it  was  not  at 
present  practical  politics,  and  meanwhile  another  ideal 
was  being  pursued.  The  fact  that  a  causal  basis  had 
been  lost  sight  of  in  the  new  theories  was  fairly  well 
known;  many  regretted  it,  and  held  that  its  restoration 
was  imperative.* 

In  rewriting  this  chapter  a  year  later  I  have  had  to 
mingle  with  this  attitude  of  indifference  an  attitude 
more  definitely  hostile  to  determinism  which  has  arisen 
from  the  acceptance  of  the  Principle  of  Indeterminacy 
(p.  220).  There  has  been  no  time  for  more  than  a  hur- 
ried examination  of  the  far-reaching  consequences  of  this 
principle;  and  I  should  have  been  reluctant  to  include 
"stop-press"  ideas  were  it  not  that  they  appear  to  clinch 
the  conception  towards  which  the  earlier  developments 
were  leading.  The  future  is  a  combination  of  the  causal 
influences  of  the  past  together  with  unpredictable  ele- 
ments— unpredictable    not    merely    because     it    is    im- 

*  A  few  days  after  the  course  of  lectures  was  completed,  Einstein 
wrote  in  his  message  on  the  Newton  Centenary,  "It  is  only  in  the  quan- 
tum theory  that  Newton's  differential  method  becomes  inadequate,  and 
indeed  strict  causality  fails  us.  But  the  last  word  has  not  yet  been  said. 
May  the  spirit  of  Newton's  method  give  us  the  power  to  restore  unison 
between  physical  reality  and  the  profoundest  characteristic  of  Newton's 
teaching — strict  causality."   (Nature,  1927,  March  26,  p.  467.) 


CAUSATION  AND  TIME'S  ARROW  295 

practicable  to  obtain  the  data  of  prediction,  but  because 
no  data  connected  causally  with  our  experience  exist. 
It  will  be  necessary  to  defend  so  remarkable  a  change  of 
opinion  at  some  length.  Meanwhile  we  may  note  that 
science  thereby  withdraws  its  moral  opposition  to  free- 
will. Those  who  maintain  a  deterministic  theory  of 
mental  activity  must  do  so  as  the  outcome  of  their  study 
of  the  mind  itself  and  not  with  the  idea  that  they  are 
thereby  making  it  more  conformable  with  our  experi- 
mental knowledge  of  the  laws  of  inorganic  nature. 

Causation  and  Time's  Arrow.  Cause  and  effect  are  closely 
bound  up  with  time's  arrow;  the  cause  must  precede 
the  effect.  The  relativity  of  time  has  not  obliterated  this 
order.  An  event  Here-Now  can  only  cause  events  in  the 
cone  of  absolute  future;  it  can  be  caused  by  events  in 
the  cone  of  absolute  past;  it  can  neither  cause  nor  be 
caused  by  events  in  the  neutral  wedge,  since  the  neces- 
sary influence  would  in  that  case  have  to  be  transmitted 
with  a  speed  faster  than  light.  But  curiously  enough  this 
elementary  notion  of  cause  and  effect  is  quite  incon- 
sistent with  a  strictly  causal  scheme.  How  can  I  cause 
an  event  in  the  absolute  future,  if  the  future  was  pre- 
determined before  I  was  born?  The  notion  evidently 
implies  that  something  may  be  born  into  the  world  at 
the  instant  Here-Now,  which  has  an  influence  extending 
throughout  the  future  cone  but  no  corresponding 
linkage  to  the  cone  of  absolute  past.  The  primary  laws 
of  physics  do  not  provide  for  any  such  one-way  linkage; 
any  alteration  in  a  prescribed  state  of  the  world  implies 
alterations  in  its  past  state  symmetrical  with  the  altera- 
tions in  its  future  state.  Thus  in  primary  physics,  which 
knows  nothing  of  time's  arrow,  there  is  no  discrimina- 
tion of  cause  and  effect;  but  events  are  connected  by  a 


296  CAUSATION 

symmetrical  causal  relation  which  is  the  same  viewed 
from  either  end. 

Primary  physics  postulates  a  strictly  causal  scheme, 
but  the  causality  is  a  symmetrical  relation  and  not  the 
one-way  relation  of  cause  and  effect.  Secondary  physics 
can  distinguish  cause  and  effect  but  its  foundation  does 
not  rest  on  a  causal  scheme  and  it  is  indifferent  as  to 
whether  or  not  strict  causality  prevails. 

The  lever  in  a  signal  box  is  moved  and  the  signal 
drops.  We  can  point  out  the  relation  of  constraint 
which  associates  the  positions  of  lever  and  signal;  we 
can  also  find  that  the  movements  are  not  synchronous, 
and  calculate  the  time-difference.  But  the  laws  of 
mechanics  do  not  ascribe  an  absolute  sign  to  this  time- 
difference;  so  far  as  they  are  concerned  we  may  quite 
well  suppose  that  the  drop  of  the  signal  causes  the  motion 
of  the  lever.  To  settle  which  is  the  cause,  we  have  two 
options.  We  can  appeal  to  the  signalman  who  is  con- 
fident that  he  made  the  mental  decision  to  pull  the  lever; 
but  this  criterion  will  only  be  valid  if  we  agree  that  there 
was  a  genuine  decision  between  two  possible  courses 
and  not  a  mere  mental  registration  of  what  was  already 
predetermined.  Or  we  can  appeal  to  secondary  law 
which  takes  note  of  the  fact  that  there  was  more  of  the 
random  element  in  the  world  when  the  signal  dropped 
than  when  the  lever  moved.  But  the  feature  of  secon- 
dary law  is  that  it  ignores  strict  causation;  it  concerns 
itself  not  with  what  must  happen  but  with  what  is 
likely  to  happen.  Thus  distinction  of  cause  and  effect 
has  no  meaning  in  the  closed  system  of  primary  laws 
of  physics;  to  get  at  it  we  have  to  break  into  the  scheme, 
introducing  considerations  of  volition  or  of  probability 
which  are  foreign  to  it.  This  is  rather  analogous  to  the 
ten  vanishing  coefficients  of  curvature  which  could  only 


CAUSATION  AND  TIME'S  ARROW  4&) 

be  recognised  if  the  closed  system  of  the  world  were 
broken  into  by  standards  foreign  to  it. 

For  convenience  I  shall  call  the  relation  of  effect  to 
cause  causation,  and  the  symmetrical  relation  which  does 
not  distinguish  between  cause  and  effect  causality.  In 
primary  physics  causality  has  completely  replaced 
causation.  Ideally  the  whole  world  past  and  future  is 
connected  into  a  deterministic  scheme  by  relations  of 
causality.  Up  till  very  recently  it  was  universally  held 
that  such  a  determinate  scheme  must  exist  (possibly 
subject  to  suspension  by  supernatural  agencies  outside 
the  scope  of  physics) ;  we  may  therefore  call  this  the 
"orthodox"  view.  It  was,  of  course,  recognised  that  we 
were  only  acquainted  with  part  of  the  structure  of  this 
causal  scheme,  but  it  was  the  settled  aim  of  theoretical 
physics  to  discover  the  whole. 

This  replacement  in  orthodox  science  of  causation  by 
causality  is  important  in  one  respect.  We  must  not  let 
causality  borrow  an  intuitive  sanction  which  really 
belongs  only  to  causation.  We  may  think  we  have  an 
intuition  that  the  same  cause  cannot  have  two  alternative 
effects;  but  we  do  not  claim  any  intuition  that  the  same 
effect  may  not  spring  from  two  alternative  causes.  For 
this  reason  the  assumption  of  a  rigid  determinateness 
enforced  by  relations  of  causality  cannot  be  said  to  be 
insisted  on  by  intuition. 

What  is  the  ground  for  so  much  ardent  faith  in  the 
orthodox  hypothesis  that  physical  phenomena  rest  ulti- 
mately on  a  scheme  of  completely  deterministic  laws? 
I  think  there  are  two  reasons — 

(i)  The  principal  laws  of  Nature  which  have  been 
discovered  are  apparently  of  this  deterministic  type, 
and  these  have  furnished  the  great  triumphs  of  physical 
prediction.     It  is  natural  to  trust  to  a  line  of  progress 


298  CAUSATION 

which  has  served  us  well  in  the  past.  Indeed  it  is  a 
healthy  attitude  to  assume  that  nothing  is  beyond  the 
scope  of  scientific  prediction  until  the  limits  of  prediction 
actually  declare  themselves. 

(2)  The  current  epistemology  of  science  presupposes 
a  deterministic  scheme  of  this  type.  To  modify  it  in- 
volves a  much  deeper  change  in  our  attitude  to  natural 
knowledge  than  the  mere  abandonment  of  an  untenable 
hypothesis. 

In  explanation  of  the  second  point  we  must  recall 
that  knowledge  of  the  physical  world  has  to  be  inferred 
from  the  nerve-messages  which  reach  our  brains,  and 
the  current  epistemology  assumes  that  there  exists  a 
determinate  scheme  of  inference  (lying  before  us 
as  an  ideal  and  gradually  being  unravelled).  But,  as  has 
already  been  pointed  out,  the  chains  of  inference  are 
simply  the  converse  of  the  chains  of  physical  causality 
by  which  distant  events  are  connected  to  the  nerve- 
messages.  If  the  scheme  of  transmission  of  these  mes- 
sages through  the  external  world  is  not  deterministic 
then  the  scheme  of  inference  as  to  their  source  cannot 
be  deterministic,  and  our  epistemology  has  been  based 
on  an  impossible  ideal.  In  that  case  our  attitude  to  the 
whole  scheme  of  natural  knowledge  must  be  profoundly 
modified. 

These  reasons  will  be  considered  at  length,  but  it  is 
convenient  to  state  here  our  answers  to  them  in  equally 
summary  form. 

(1)  In  recent  times  some  of  the  greatest  triumphs  of 
physical  prediction  have  been  furnished  by  admittedly 
statistical  laws  which  do  not  rest  on  a  basis  of  causality. 
Moreover  the  great  laws  hitherto  accepted  as  causal 
appear  on  minuter  examination  to  be  of  statistical 
character. 


PREDICTABILITY  OF  EVENTS  299 

(2)  Whether  or  not  there  is  a  causal  scheme  at  the 
base  of  atomic  phenomena,  modern  atomic  theory  is  not 
now  attempting  to  find  it;  and  it  is  making  rapid  prog- 
ress because  it  no  longer  sets  this  up  as  a  practical  aim. 
We  are  in  the  position  of  holding  an  epistemological 
theory  of  natural  knowledge  which  does  not  correspond 
to  actual  aim  of  current  scientific  investigation. 

Predictability  of  Events.  Let  us  examine  a  typical  case 
of  successful  scientific  prediction.  A  total  eclipse  of  the 
sun  visible  in  Cornwall  is  prophesied  for  1 1  August 
1999.  It  is  generally  supposed  that  this  eclipse  is 
already  predetermined  by  the  present  configuration  of 
the  sun,  earth  and  moon.  I  do  not  wish  to  arouse 
unnecessary  misgiving  as  to  whether  the  eclipse  will 
come  off.  I  expect  it  will;  but  let  us  examine  the  grounds 
of  expectation.  It  is  predicted  as  a  consequence  of  the 
law  of  gravitation — a  law  which  we  found  in  chapter  vil 
to  be  a  mere  truism.  That  does  not  diminish  the  value 
of  the  prediction;  but  it  does  suggest  that  we  may  not  be 
able  to  pose  as  such  marvellous  prophets  when  we  come 
up  against  laws  which  are  not  mere  truisms.  I  might 
venture  to  predict  that  2  +  2  will  be  equal  to  4  even  in 
1999;  but  if  this  should  prove  correct  it  will  not  help 
to  convince  anyone  that  the  universe  (or,  if  you  like,  the 
human  mind)  is  governed  by  laws  of  deterministic  type. 
I  suppose  that  in  the  most  erratically  governed  world 
something  can  be  predicted  if  truisms  are  not  ex- 
cluded. 

But  we  have  to  look  deeper  than  this.  The  law  of 
gravitation  is  only  a  truism  when  regarded  from  a 
macroscopic  point  of  view.  It  presupposes  space,  and 
measurement  with  gross  material  or  optical  arrange- 
ments.    It  cannot  be  refined  to  an  accuracy  beyond  the 


300  CAUSATION 

limits  of  these  gross  appliances;  so  that  it  is  a  truism 
with  a  probable  error — small,  but  not  infinitely  small. 
The  classical  laws  hold  good  in  the  limit  when  exceed- 
ingly large  quantum  numbers  are  involved.  The  system 
comprising  the  sun,  earth  and  moon  has  exceedingly 
high  state-number  (p.  198);  and  the  predictability  of 
its  configurations  is  not  characteristic  of  natural  pheno- 
mena in  general  but  of  those  involving  great  numbers 
of  atoms  of  action — such  that  we  are  concerned  not 
with  individual  but  with  average  behaviour. 

Human  life  is  proverbially  uncertain;  few  things  are 
more  certain  than  the  solvency  of  a  life-insurance  com- 
pany. The  average  law  is  so  trustworthy  that  it  may  be 
considered  predestined  that  half  the  children  now  born 
will  survive  the  age  of  x  years.  But  that  does  not  tell  us 
whether  the  span  of  life  of  young  A.  McB.  is  already 
written  in  the  book  of  fate,  or  whether  there  is  still  time 
to  alter  it  by  teaching  him  not  to  run  in  front  of  motor- 
buses.  The  eclipse  in  1999  is  as  safe  as  the  balance  of 
a  life-insurance  company;  the  next  quantum  jump  of  an 
atom  is  as  uncertain  as  your  life  and  mine. 

We  are  thus  in  a  position  to  answer  the  main  argu- 
ment for  a  predetermination  of  the  future,  viz.  that 
observation  shows  the  laws  of  Nature  to  be  of  a  type 
which  leads  to  definite  predictions  of  the  future,  and  it 
is  reasonable  to  expect  that  any  laws  which  remain 
undiscovered  will  conform  to  the  same  type.  For  when 
we  ask  what  is  the  characteristic  of  the  phenomena  that 
have  been  successfully  predicted,  the  answer  is  that  they 
are  effects  depending  on  the  average  configurations  of  vast 
numbers  of  individual  entities.  But  averages  are  pre- 
dictable because  they  are  averages,  irrespective  of  the 
type  of  government  of  the  phenomena  underlying 
them. 


PREDICTABILITY  OF  EVENTS  301 

Considering  an  atom  alone  in  the  world  in  State  3, 
the  classical  theory  would  have  asked,  and  hoped  to 
answer,  the  question,  What  will  it  do  next?  The  quan- 
tum theory  substitutes  the  question,  Which  will  it  do 
next?  Because  it  admits  only  two  lower  states  for  the 
atom  to  go  to.  Further,  it  makes  no  attempt  to  find  a 
definite  answer,  but  contents  itself  with  calculating  the 
respective  odds  on  the  jumps  to  State  1  and  State  2. 
The  quantum  physicist  does  not  fill  the  atom  with 
gadgets  for  directing  its  future  behaviour,  as  the  classical 
physicist  would  have  done;  he  fills  it  with  gadgets  de- 
termining the  odds  on  its  future  behaviour.  He  studies 
the  art  of  the  bookmaker  not  of  the  trainer. 

Thus  in  the  structure  of  the  world  as  formulated  in 
the  new  quantum  theory  it  is  predetermined  that  of 
500  atoms  now  in  State  3,  approximately  400  will  go 
on  to  State  1  and  100  to  State  2 — in  so  far  as  anything 
subject  to  chance  fluctuations  can  be  said  to  be  pre- 
determined. The  odds  of  4  to  1  find  their  appropriate 
representation  in  the  picture  of  the  atom;  that  is  to  say, 
something  symbolic  of  a  4  :  1  ratio  is  present  in  each  of 
the  500  atoms.  But  there  are  no  marks  distinguishing 
the  atoms  belonging  to  the  group  of  100  from  the  400. 
Probably  most  physicists  would  take  the  view  that 
although  the  marks  are  not  yet  shown  in  the  picture, 
they  are  nevertheless  present  in  Nature;  they  belong  to 
an  elaboration  of  the  theory  which  will  come  in  good 
time.  The  marks,  of  course,  need  not  be  in  the  atom 
itself;  they  may  be  in  the  environment  which  will 
interact  with  it.  For  example,  we  may  load  dice  in  such 
a  way  that  the  odds  are  4  to  1  on  throwing  a  6.  Both 
those  dice  which  turn  up  6  and  those  which  do  not 
have  these  odds  written  in  their  constitution — by  a 
displaced  position  of  the  centre  of  gravity.     The  result 


302  CAUSATION 

of  a  particular  throw  is  not  marked  in  the  dice;  never- 
theless it  is  strictly  causal  (apart  perhaps  from  the 
human  element  involved  in  throwing  the  dice)  being  de- 
termined by  the  external  influences  which  are  concerned. 
Our  own  position  at  this  stage  is  that  future  develop- 
ments of  physics  may  reveal  such  causal  marks  (either 
in  the  atom  or  in  the  influences  outside  it)  or  it  may  not. 
Hitherto  whenever  we  have  thought  we  have  detected 
causal  marks  in  natural  phenomena  they  have  always 
proved  spurious,  the  apparent  determinism  having  come 
about  in  another  way.  Therefore  we  are  inclined  to 
regard  favourably  the  possibility  that  there  may  be  no 
causal  marks  anywhere. 

But,  it  will  be  said,  it  is  inconceivable  that  an  atom 
can  be  so  evenly  balanced  between  two  alternative 
courses  that  nowhere  in  the  world  as  yet  is  there  any 
trace  of  the  ultimately  deciding  factor.  This  is  an  ap- 
peal to  intuition  and  it  may  fairly  be  countered  with 
another  appeal  to  intuition.  I  have  an  intuition  much 
more  immediate  than  any  relating  to  the  objects  of  the 
physical  world;  this  tells  me  that  nowhere  in  the  world 
as  yet  is  there  any  trace  of  a  deciding  factor  as  to 
whether  I  am  going  to  lift  my  right  hand  or  my  left. 
It  depends  on  an  unfettered  act  of  volition  not  yet  made 
or  foreshadowed.*  My  intuition  is  that  the  future  is 
able  to  bring  forth  deciding  factors  which  are  not 
secretly  hidden  in  the  past. 

The  position  is  that  the  laws  governing  the  micro- 
scopic elements  of  the  physical  world — individual 
atoms,  electrons,  quanta — do  not  make  definite  pre- 
dictions as  to  what  the  individual  will  do  next.     I  am 

*  It  is  fair  to  assume  the  trustworthiness  of  this  intuition  in  answering 
an  argument  which  appeals  to  intuition;  the  assumption  would  beg  the 
question  if  we  were  urging  the  argument  independently. 


THE  NEW  EPISTEMOLOGICAL  OUTLOOK     303 

here  speaking  of  the  laws  that  have  been  actually  dis- 
covered and  formulated  on  the  old  quantum  theory  and 
the  new.  These  laws  indicate  several  possibilities  in  the 
future  and  state  the  odds  on  each.  In  general  the  odds 
are  moderately  balanced  and  are  not  tempting  to  an 
aspiring  prophet.  But  short  odds  on  the  behaviour  of 
individuals  combine  into  very  long  odds  on  suitably 
selected  statistics  of  a  number  of  individuals;  and  the 
wary  prophet  can  find  predictions  of  this  kind  on  which 
to  stake  his  credit — without  serious  risk.  All  the  success- 
ful predictions  hitherto  attributed  to  causality  are  trace- 
able to  this.  It  is  quite  true  that  the  quantum  laws  for 
individuals  are  not  incompatible  with  causality;  they 
merely  ignore  it.  But  if  we  take  advantage  of  this 
indifference  to  reintroduce  determinism  at  the  basis  of 
world  structure  it  is  because  our  philosophy  predisposes 
us  that  way,  not  because  we  know  of  any  experimental 
evidence  in  its  favour. 

We  might  for  illustration  make  a  comparison  with 
the  doctrine  of  predestination.  That  theological  doc- 
trine, whatever  may  be  said  against  it,  has  hitherto 
seemed  to  blend  harmoniously  with  the  predetermination 
of  the  material  universe.  But  if  we  were  to  appeal  to 
the  new  conception  of  physical  law  to  settle  this  question 
by  analogy  the  answer  would  be : — The  individual  is  not 
predestined  to  arrive  at  either  of  the  two  states,  which 
perhaps  may  here  be  sufficiently  discriminated  as 
State  1  and  State  2;  the  most  that  can  be  considered 
already  settled  is  the  respective  odds  on  his  reaching 
these  states. 

The  New  Epistemological  Outlook.  Scientific  investiga- 
tion does  not  lead  to  knowledge  of  the  intrinsic  nature 
of  things.     "Whenever  we  state  the  properties  of  a  body 


304  CAUSATION 

in  terms  of  physical  quantities  we  are  imparting  know- 
ledge of  the  response  of  various  metrical  indicators  to 
its  presence  and  nothing  more"  (p.  257).  But  if  a  body- 
is  not  acting  according  to  strict  causality,  if  there  is  an 
element  of  uncertainty  as  to  the  response  of  the  indica- 
tors, we  seem  to  have  cut  away  the  ground  for  this  kind  of 
knowledge.  It  is  not  predetermined  what  will  be  the 
reading  of  the  weighing-machine  if  the  body  is  placed 
on  it,  therefore  the  body  has  no  definite  mass;  nor  where 
it  will  be  found  an  instant  hence,  therefore  it  has  no 
definite  velocity;  nor  where  the  rays  now  being  reflected 
from  it  will  converge  in  the  microscope,  therefore  it  has 
no  definite  position;  and  so  on.  It  is  no  use  answering 
that  the  body  really  has  a  definite  mass,  velocity, 
position,  etc.,  which  we  are  unaware  of;  that  statement, 
if  it  means  anything,  refers  to  an  intrinsic  nature  of 
things  outside  the  scope  of  scientific  knowledge.  We 
cannot  infer  these  properties  with  precision  from  any- 
thing that  we  can  be  aware  of,  because  the  breach  of 
causality  has  broken  the  chain  of  inference.  Thus  our 
knowledge  of  the  response  of  indicators  to  the  presence 
of  the  body  is  non-existent;  therefore  we  cannot  assert 
knowledge  of  it  at  all.  So  what  is  the  use  of  talking 
about  it?  The  body  which  was  to  be  the  abstraction  of 
all  these  (as  yet  unsettled)  pointer  readings  has  become 
superfluous  in  the  physical  world.  That  is  the  dilemma 
into  which  the  old  epistemology  leads  us  as  soon  as  we 
begin  to  doubt  strict  causality. 

In  phenomena  on  a  gross  scale  this  difficulty  can  be 
got  round.  A  body  may  have  no  definite  position  but 
yet  have  within  close  limits  an  extremely  probable 
position.  When  the  probabilities  are  large  the  substitu- 
tion of  probability  for  certainty  makes  little  difference; 
it  adds  only   a   negligible  haziness   to   the  world.      But 


THE  NEW  EPISTEMOLOGICAL  OUTLOOK     305 

though  the  practical  change  is  unimportant  there  are 
fundamental  theoretical  consequences.  All  probabilities 
rest  on  a  basis  of  a  priori  probability,  and  we  cannot  say 
whether  probabilities  are  large  or  small  without  having 
assumed  such  a  basis.  In  agreeing  to  accept  those  of  our 
calculated  probabilities  which  are  very  high  as  virtually 
equivalent  to  certainties  on  the  old  scheme,  we  are  as  it 
were  making  our  adopted  basis  of  a  priori  probability 
a  constituent  of  the  world-structure — adding  to  the 
world  a  kind  of  symbolic  texture  that  cannot  be  ex- 
pressed on  the  old  scheme. 

On  the  atomic  scale  of  phenomena  the  probabilities 
are  in  general  well-balanced,  and  there  are  no  "naps" 
for  the  scientific  punter  to  put  his  shirt  on.  If  a  body  is 
still  defined  as  a  bundle  of  pointer  readings  (or  highly 
probable  pointer  readings)  there  are  no  "bodies"  on 
the  atomic  scale.  All  that  we  can  extract  is  a  bundle  of 
probabilities.  That  is  in  fact  just  how  Schrodinger  tries 
to  picture  the  atom — as  a  wave  centre  of  his  probability 
entity  i|>. 

We  commonly  have  had  to  deal  with  probabilities 
which  arise  through  ignorance.  With  fuller  knowledge 
we  should  sweep  away  the  references  to  probability  and 
substitute  the  exact  facts.  But  it  appears  to  be  a  funda- 
mental point  in  Schrodinger's  theory  that  his  probabili- 
ties are  not  to  be  replaced  in  that  way.  When  his  ip  is 
sufficiently  concentrated  it  indicates  the  point  where  the 
electron  is;  when  it  is  diffused  it  gives  only  a  vague 
indication  of  the  position.  But  this  vague  indication  is 
not  something  which  ideally  ought  to  be  replaced  by 
exact  knowledge;  it  is  ip  itself  which  acts  as  the  source 
of  the  light  emitted  from  the  atom,  the  period  of  the 
light  being  that  of  the  beats  of  i|>.  I  think  this  means 
that  the  spread  of  ty  is  not  a  symbol  for  uncertainty  aris- 


306  CAUSATION 

ing  through  lack  of  information;  it  is  a  symbol  for 
causal  failure — an  indeterminacy  of  behaviour  which  is 
part  of  the  character  of  the  atom. 

We  have  two  chief  ways  of  learning  about  the  interior 
of  the  atom.  We  can  observe  electrons  entering  or 
leaving,  and  we  can  observe  light  entering  or  leaving. 
Bohr  has  assumed  a  structure  connected  by  strictly 
causal  law  with  the  first  phenomenon,  Heisenberg  and 
his  followers  with  the  second.  If  the  two  structures  were 
identifiable  then  the  atom  wrould  involve  a  complete 
causal  connection  of  the  two  types  of  phenomena.  But 
apparently  no  such  causal  linkage  exists.  Therefore  we 
have  to  be  content  with  a  correlation  in  which  the 
entities  of  the  one  model  represent  probabilities  in  the 
second  model.  There  are  perhaps  details  in  the  two 
theories  which  do  not  quite  square  with  this;  but  it 
seems  to  express  the  ideal  to  be  aimed  at  in  describing 
the  laws  of  an  incompletely  causal  world,  viz.  that  the 
causal  source  of  one  phenomenon  shall  represent  the 
probability  of  causal  source  of  another  phenomenon. 
Schrodinger's  theory  has  given  at  least  a  strong  hint 
that  the  actual  world  is  controlled  on  this  plan. 

The  Principle  of  Indeterminacy.  Thus  far  we  have 
shown  that  modern  physics  is  drifting  away  from  the 
postulate  that  the  future  is  predetermined,  ignoring  it 
rather  than  deliberately  rejecting  it.  With  the  discovery 
of  the  Principle  of  Indeterminacy  (p.  220)  its  attitude 
has  become  more  definitely  hostile. 

Let  us  take  the  simplest  case  in  which  we  think  we 
can  predict  the  future.  Suppose  that  we  have  a  particle 
with  known  position  and  velocity  at  the  present  instant. 
Assuming  that  nothing  interferes  with  it  we  can  predict 
the  position  at  a  subsequent  instant.      (Strictly  the  non- 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  INDETERMINACY       307 

interference  would  be  a  subject  for  another  prediction, 
but  to  simplify  matters  we  shall  concede  it.)  It  is  just 
this  simple  prediction  which  the  principle  of  indeter- 
minacy expressly  forbids.  It  states  that  we  cannot  know 
accurately  both  the  velocity  and  position  of  a  particle 
at  the  present  instant. 

At  first  sight  there  seems  to  be  an  inconsistency. 
There  is  no  limit  to  the  accuracy  with  which  we  may 
know  the  position,  provided  that  we  do  not  want  to 
know  the  velocity  also.  Very  well;  let  us  make  a  highly 
accurate  determination  of  position  now,  and  after 
waiting  a  moment  make  another  highly  accurate  deter- 
mination of  position.  Comparing  the  two  accurate 
positions  we  compute  the  accurate  velocity — and  snap 
our  fingers  at  the  principle  of  indeterminacy.  This 
velocity,  however,  is  of  no  use  for  prediction,  because  in 
making  the  second  accurate  determination  of  position 
we  have  rough-handled  the  particle  so  much  that  it  no 
longer  has  the  velocity  we  calculated.  //  is  a  purely 
retrospective  velocity.  The  velocity  does  not  exist  in  the 
present  tense  but  in  the  future  perfect;  it  never  exists, 
it  never  will  exist,  but  a  time  may  come  when  it  will  have 
existed.  There  is  no  room  for  it  in  Fig.  4  which  contains 
an  Absolute  Future  and  an  Absolute  Past  but  not  an 
Absolute  Future  Perfect. 

The  velocity  which  we  attribute  to  a  particle  now 
can  be  regarded  as  an  anticipation  of  its  future  positions. 
To  say  that  it  is  unknowable  (except  with  a  certain 
degree  of  inaccuracy)  is  to  say  that  the  future  cannot  be 
anticipated.  Immediately  the  future  is  accomplished, 
so  that  it  is  no  longer  an  anticipation,  the  velocity  be- 
comes knowable. 

The  classical  view  that  a  particle  necessarily  has  a 
definite    (but   not   necessarily   knowable)    velocity  now, 


308  CAUSATION 

amounts  to  disguising  a  piece  of  the  unknown  future  as 
an  unknowable  element  of  the  present.  Classical  physics 
foists  a  deterministic  scheme  on  us  by  a  trick;  it  smuggles 
the  unknown  future  into  the  present,  trusting  that  we 
shall  not  press  an  inquiry  as  to  whether  it  has  become 
any  more  knowable  that  way. 

The  same  principle  extends  to  every  kind  of  pheno- 
menon that  we  attempt  to  predict,  so  long  as  the  need 
for  accuracy  is  not  buried  under  a  mass  of  averages.  To 
every  co-ordinate  there  corresponds  a  momentum,  and 
by  the  principle  of  indeterminacy  the  more  accurately 
the  co-ordinate  is  known  the  less  accurately  the  momen- 
tum is  known.  Nature  thus  provides  that  knowledge 
of  one-half  of  the  world  will  ensure  ignorance  of  the 
other  half — ignorance  which,  we  have  seen,  may  be 
remedied  later  when  the  same  part  of  the  world  is  con- 
templated retrospectively.  We  can  scarcely  rest  content 
with  a  picture  of  the  world  which  includes  so  much  that 
cannot  be  known.  We  have  been  trying  to  get  rid  of 
unknowable  things,  i.e.  all  conceptions  which  have  no 
causal  connection  with  our  experience.  We  have  elimi- 
nated velocity  through  aether,  "right"  frames  of  space, 
etc.,  for  this  reason.  This  vast  new  unknowable  element 
must  likewise  be  swept  out  of  the  Present.  Its  proper 
place  is  in  the  Future  because  then  it  will  no 
longer  be  unknowable.  It  has  been  put  in  prematurely 
as  an  anticipation  of  that  which  cannot  be  antici- 
pated. 

In  assessing  whether  the  symbols  which  the  physicist 
has  scattered  through  the  external  world  are  adequate  to 
predetermine  the  future,  we  must  be  on  our  guard 
against  retrospective  symbols.  It  is  easy  to  prophesy 
after  the  event. 


NATURAL  AND  SUPERNATURAL  309 

Natural  and  Supernatural.  A  rather  serious  consequence 
of  dropping  causality  in  the  external  world  is  that  it 
leaves  us  with  no  clear  distinction  between  the  Natural 
and  the  Supernatural.  In  an  earlier  chapter  I  compared 
the  invisible  agent  invented  to  account  for  the  tug  of 
gravitation  to  a  "demon".  Is  a  view  of  the  world  which 
admits  such  an  agent  any  more  scientific  than  that  of  a 
savage  who  attributes  all  that  he  finds  mysterious  in 
Nature  to  the  work  of  invisible  demons?  The  New- 
tonian physicist  had  a  valid  defence.  He  could  point 
out  that  his  demon  Gravitation  was  supposed  to  act 
according  to  fixed  causal  laws  and  was  therefore  not  to 
be  compared  with  the  irresponsible  demons  of  the 
savage.  Once  a  deviation  from  strict  causality  is  ad- 
mitted the  distinction  melts  away.  I  suppose  that  the 
savage  would  admit  that  his  demon  was  to  some  extent 
a  creature  of  habit  and  that  it  would  be  possible  to  make 
a  fair  guess  as  to  what  he  would  do  in  the  future;  but 
that  sometimes  he  would  show  a  will  of  his  own.  It  is 
that  imperfect  consistency  which  formerly  disqualified 
him  from  admission  as  an  entity  of  physics  along  with 
his  brother  Gravitation. 

That  is  largely  why  there  has  been  so  much  bother 
about  "me";  because  I  have,  or  am  persuaded  that  I 
have,  "a  will  of  my  own".  Either  the  physicist  must 
leave  his  causal  scheme  at  the  mercy  of  supernatural 
interference  from  me,  or  he  must  explain  away  my 
supernatural  qualities.  In  self-defence  the  materialist 
favoured  the  latter  course;  he  decided  that  I  was  not 
supernatural — only  complicated.  We  on  the  other  hand 
have  concluded  that  there  is  no  strict  causal  behaviour 
anywhere.  We  can  scarcely  deny  the  charge  that  in 
abolishing  the  criterion  of  causality  we  are  opening  the 
door  to  the  savage's  demons.     It  is  a  serious  step,  but 


310  CAUSATION 

I  do  not  think  it  means  the  end  of  all  true  science.  After 
all  if  they  try  to  enter  we  can  pitch  them  out  again,  as 
Einstein  pitched  out  the  respectable  causal  demon  who 
called  himself  Gravitation.  It  is  a  privation  to  be  no 
longer  able  to  stigmatise  certain  views  as  unscientific 
superstition;  but  we  are  still  allowed,  if  the  circumstances 
justify  it,  to  reject  them  as  bad  science. 

Volition.  From  the  philosophic  point  of  view  it  is  of  deep 
interest  to  consider  how  this  affects  the  freedom  of  the 
human  mind  and  spirit.  A  complete  determinism  of 
the  material  universe  cannot  be  divorced  from  deter- 
minism of  the  mind.  Take,  for  example,  the  prediction 
of  the  weather  this  time  next  year.  The  prediction  is 
not  likely  ever  to  become  practicable,  but  "orthodox" 
physicists  are  not  yet  convinced  that  it  is  theoretically 
impossible;  they  hold  that  next  year's  weather  is  already 
predetermined.  We  should  require  extremely  detailed 
knowledge  of  present  conditions,  since  a  small  local 
deviation  can  exert  an  ever-expanding  influence. 
We  must  examine  the  state  of  the  sun  so  as  to  predict 
the  fluctuations  in  the  heat  and  corpuscular  radiation 
which  it  sends  us.  We  must  dive  into  the  bowels  of  the 
earth  to  be  forewarned  of  volcanic  eruptions  which  may 
spread  a  dust  screen  over  the  atmosphere  as  Mt.  Katmai 
did  some  years  ago.  But  further  we  must  penetrate  into 
the  recesses  of  the  human  mind.  A  coal  strike,  a  great 
war,  may  directly  change  the  conditions  of  the  atmo- 
sphere; a  lighted  match  idly  thrown  away  may  cause 
deforestation  which  will  change  the  rainfall  and  climate. 
There  can  be  no  fully  deterministic  control  of  inorganic 
phenomena  unless  the  determinism  governs  mind  itself. 
Conversely  if  we  wish  to  emancipate  mind  we  must  to 
some  extent  emancipate  the  material  world  also.     There 


VOLITION  311 

appears  to  be  no  longer  any  obstacle  to  this  emanci- 
pation. 

Let  us  look  more  closely  into  the  problem  of  how  the 
mind  gets  a  grip  on  material  atoms  so  that  movements 
of  the  body  and  limbs  can  be  controlled  by  its  volition. 
I  think  we  may  now  feel  quite  satisfied  that  the  volition 
is  genuine.  The  materialist  view  was  that  the  motions 
which  appear  to  be  caused  by  our  volition  are  really 
reflex  actions  controlled  by  the  material  processes  in  the 
brain,  the  act  of  will  being  an  inessential  side  pheno- 
menon occurring  simultaneously  with  the  physical 
phenomena.  But  this  assumes  that  the  result  of  apply- 
ing physical  laws  to  the  brain  is  fully  determinate.  It  is 
meaningless  to  say  that  the  behaviour  of  a  conscious 
brain  is  precisely  the  same  as  that  of  a  mechanical  brain 
if  the  behaviour  of  a  mechanical  brain  is  left  undeter- 
mined. If  the  laws  of  physics  are  not  strictly  causal  the 
most  that  can  be  said  is  that  the  behaviour  of  the 
conscious  brain  is  one  of  the  possible  behaviours  of  a 
mechanical  brain.  Precisely  so;  and  the  decision  between 
the  possible  behaviours  is  what  we  call  volition. 

Perhaps  you  will  say,  When  the  decision  of  an  atom 
is  made  between  its  possible  quantum  jumps,  is  that 
also  "volition"?  Scarcely;  the  analogy  is  altogether  too 
remote.  The  position  is  that  both  for  the  brain  and  the 
atom  there,  is  nothing  in  the  physical  world,  i.e.  the 
world  of  pointer  readings,  to  predetermine  the  decision; 
the  decision  is  a  fact  of  the  physical  world  with  con- 
sequences in  the  future  but  not  causally  connected  to 
the  past.  In  the  case  of  the  brain  we  have  an  insight 
into  a  mental  world  behind  the  world  of  pointer  readings 
and  in  that  world  we  get  a  new  picture  of  the  fact  of 
decision  which  must  be  taken  as  revealing  its  real 
nature — if    the   words   real   nature    have    any    meaning. 


312  CAUSATION 

For  the  atom  we  have  no  such  insight  into  what  is 
behind  the  pointer  readings.  We  believe  that  behind 
all  pointer  readings  there  is  a  background  continuous 
with  the  background  of  the  brain;  but  there  is  no  more 
ground  for  calling  the  background  of  the  spontaneous 
behaviour  of  the  atom  "volition"  than  for  calling  the 
background  of  its  causal  behaviour  "reason".  It  should 
be  understood  that  we  are  not  attempting  to  reintroduce 
in  the  background  the  strict  causality  banished  from 
the  pointer  readings.  In  the  one  case  in  which  we  have 
any  insight — the  background  of  the  brain — we  have 
no  intention  of  giving  up  the  freedom  of  the  mind  and 
will.  Similarly  we  do  not  suggest  that  the  marks  of 
predestination  of  the  atom,  not  found  in  the  pointer 
readings,  exist  undetectable  in  the  unknown  back- 
ground. To  the  question  whether  I  would  admit  that 
the  cause  of  the  decision  of  the  atom  has  something  in 
common  with  the  cause  of  the  decision  of  the  brain, 
I  would  simply  answer  that  there  is  no  cause.  In  the 
case  of  the  brain  I  have  a  deeper  insight  into  the 
decision;  this  insight  exhibits  it  as  volition,  i.e.  some- 
thing outside  causality. 

A  mental  decision  to  turn  right  or  turn  left  starts  one 
of  two  alternative  sets  of  impulses  along  the  nerves  to 
the  feet.  At  some  brain  centre  the  course  of  behaviour 
of  certain  atoms  or  elements  of  the  physical  world  is 
directly  determined  for  them  by  the  mental  decision — 
or,  one  may  say,  the  scientific  description  of  that  be- 
haviour is  the  metrical  aspect  of  the  decision.  It  would 
be  a  possible  though  difficult  hypothesis  to  assume  that 
very  few  atoms  (or  possibly  only  one  atom)  have  this 
direct  contact  with  the  conscious  decision,  and  that 
these  few  atoms  serve  as  a  switch  to  deflect  the  material 
world  from  one  course  to  the  other.     But  it  is  physically 


MIND  AND  STATISTICAL  LAWS  313 

improbable  that  each  atom  has  its  duty  in  the  brain  so 
precisely  allotted  that  the  control  of  its  behaviour  would 
prevail  over  all  possible  irregularities  of  the  other  atoms. 
If  I  have  at  all  rightly  understood  the  processes  of  my 
own  mind,  there  is  no  finicking  with  individual  atoms. 
I  do  not  think  that  our  decisions  are  precisely 
balanced  on  the  conduct  of  certain  key-atoms.  Could 
we  pick  out  one  atom  in  Einstein's  brain  and  say  that 
if  it  had  made  the  wrong  quantum  jump  there  would 
have  been  a  corresponding  flaw  in  the  theory  of  rela- 
tivity? Having  regard  to  the  physical  influences  of 
temperature  and  promiscuous  collision  it  is  impossible 
to  maintain  this.  It  seems  that  we  must  attribute  to  the 
mind  power  not  only  to  decide  the  behaviour  of  atoms 
individually  but  to  affect  systematically  large  groups — 
in  fact  to  tamper  with  the  odds  on  atomic  behaviour. 
This  has  always  been  one  of  the  most  dubious  points 
in  the  theory  of  the  interaction  of  mind  and  matter. 

Interference  with  Statistical  Laws.  Has  the  mind  power 
to  set  aside  statistical  laws  which  hold  in  inorganic 
matter?  Unless  this  is  granted  its  opportunity  of  inter- 
ference seems  to  be  too  circumscribed  to  bring  about 
the  results  which  are  observed  to  follow  from  mental 
decisions.  But  the  admission  involves  a  genuine 
physical  difference  between  inorganic  and  organic  (or, 
at  any  rate,  conscious)  matter.  I  would  prefer  to  avoid 
this  hypothesis,  but  it  is  necessary  to  face  the  issue 
squarely.  The  indeterminacy  recognised  in  modern 
quantum  theory  is  only  a  partial  step  towards  freeing 
our  actions  from  deterministic  control.  To  use  an 
analogy — we  have  admitted  an  uncertainty  which  may 
take  or  spare  human  lives;  but  we  have  yet  to  find  an 
uncertainty  which  may  upset  the  expectations  of  a  life- 


3H  CAUSATION 

insurance  company.  Theoretically  the  one  uncertainty 
might  lead  to  the  other,  as  when  the  fate  of  millions 
turned  on  the  murders  at  Sarajevo.  But  the  hypothesis 
that  the  mind  operates  through  two  or  three  key-atoms 
in  the  brain  is  too  desperate  a  way  of  escape  for  us,  and 
I  reject  it  for  the  reasons  already  stated. 

It  is  one  thing  to  allow  the  mind  to  direct  an  atom 
between  two  courses  neither  of  which  would  be  im- 
probable for  an  inorganic  atom;  it  is  another  thing  to 
allow  it  to  direct  a  crowd  of  atoms  into  a  configuration 
which  the  secondary  laws  of  physics  would  set  aside  as 
"too  improbable".  Here  the  improbability  is  that  a 
large  number  of  entities  each  acting  independently 
should  conspire  to  produce  the  result;  it  is  like  the 
improbability  of  the  atoms  finding  themselves  by  chance 
all  in  one  half  of  a  vessel.  We  must  suppose  that  in  the 
physical  part  of  the  brain  immediately  affected  by  a 
mental  decision  there  is  some  kind  of  interdependence 
of  behaviour  of  the  atoms  which  is  not  present  in 
inorganic  matter. 

I  do  not  wish  to  minimise  the  seriousness  of  admitting 
this  difference  between  living  and  dead  matter.  But 
I  think  that  the  difficulty  has  been  eased  a  little,  if  it 
has  not  been  removed.  To  leave  the  atom  constituted  as 
it  was  but  to  interfere  with  the  probability  of  its  un- 
determined behaviour,  does  not  seem  quite  so  drastic 
an  interference  with  natural  law  as  other  modes  of 
mental  interference  that  have  been  suggested.  (Perhaps 
that  is  only  because  we  do  not  understand  enough  about 
these  probabilities  to  realise  the  heinousness  of  our 
suggestion.)  Unless  it  belies  its  name,  probability  can 
be  modified  in  ways  which  ordinary  physical  entities 
would  not  admit  of.  There  can  be  no  unique  probability 
attached  to  any  event  or  behaviour;  we  can  only  speak 


MIND  AND  STATISTICAL  LAWS  315 

of  "probability  in  the  light  of  certain  given  informa- 
tion", and  the  probability  alters  according  to  the  extent 
of  the  information.  It  is,  I  think,  one  of  the  most  un- 
satisfactory features  of  the  new  quantum  theory  in  its 
present  stage  that  it  scarcely  seems  to  recognise  this 
fact,  and  leaves  us  to  guess  at  the  basis  of  information 
to  which  its  probability  theorems  are  supposed  to  refer. 

Looking  at  it  from  another  aspect — if  the  unity  of 
a  man's  consciousness  is  not  an  illusion,  there  must  be 
some  corresponding  unity  in  the  relations  of  the  mind- 
stuff  which  is  behind  the  pointer  readings.  Applying 
our  measures  of  relation  structure,  as  in  chapter  XI, 
we  shall  build  matter  and  fields  of  force  obeying 
identically  the  principal  field-laws;  the  atoms  will 
individually  be  in  no  way  different  from  those  which 
are  without  this  unity  in  the  background.  But  it  seems 
plausible  that  when  we  consider  their  collective  be- 
haviour we  shall  have  to  take  account  of  the  broader 
unifying  trends  in  the  mind-stuff,  and  not  expect  the 
statistical  results  to  agree  with  those  appropriate  to 
structures  of  haphazard  origin. 

I  think  that  even  a  materialist  must  reach  a  conclusion 
not  unlike  ours  if  he  fairly  faces  the  problem.  He  will 
need  in  the  physical  world  something  to  stand  for  a 
symbolic  unity  of  the  atoms  associated  with  an  individual 
consciousness,  which  does  not  exist  for  atoms  not  so 
associated — a  unity  which  naturally  upsets  physical 
predictions  abased  on  the  hypothesis  of  random  dis- 
connection. For  he  has  not  only  to  translate  into 
material  configurations  the  multifarious  thoughts  and 
images  of  the  mind,  but  must  surely  not  neglect  to  find 
some  kind  of  physical  substitute  for  the  Ego. 


Chapter  XV 

SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM 

One  day   I   happened  to   be   occupied  with   the   subject 

of  "Generation  of  Waves  by  Wind".  I  took  down  the 

standard    treatise    on    hydrodynamics,  and    under    that 
heading  I  read — 

The  equations  (12)  and  (13)  of  the  preceding  Art.  enable  us 
to  examine  a  related  question  of  some  interest,  viz.  the  generation 
and  maintenance  of  waves  against  viscosity,  by  suitable  forces 
applied  to  the  surface. 

If  the  external  forces  p'yy,  p'^  be  given  multiples  of  «***+**, 
where  k  and  a  are  prescribed,  the  equations  in  question  determine 
A  and  C,  and  thence,  by  (9)  the  value  of  tj.    Thus  we  find 

P'vv  _  (^  +  2yffflS  +  Q2)  A  -  i  ((T2  +  2vkma)  C 
gprj ""  gk(J-  iC)  l 

£*v___a     2hk2J  +  (a  +  2yg|  C 
gprj-gk'  (J-iQ  " 

where  o2  has  been  written  for  gk  -\-  Tr  kz  as  before.  .  .  . 

And  so  on  for  two  pages.  At  the  end  it  is  made  clear 
that  a  wind  of  less  than  half  a  mile  an  hour  will  leave 
the  surface  unruffled.  At  a  mile  an  hour  the  surface  is 
covered  with  minute  corrugations  due  to  capillary  waves 
which  decay  immediately  the  disturbing  cause  ceases. 
At  two  miles  an  hour  the  gravity  waves  appear.  As 
the  author  modestly  concludes,  "Our  theoretical  investi- 
gations give  considerable  insight  into  the  incipient  stages 
of  wave-formation". 

On  another  occasion  the  same  subject  of  "Generation 

316 


SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM  317 

of  Waves  by  Wind"   was   in  my  mind;  but  this   time 
another  book  was  more  appropriate,  and  I  read — 

There  are  waters  blown  by  changing  winds  to  laughter 
And  lit  by  the  rich  skies,  all  day.    And  after, 

Frost,  with  a  gesture,  stays  the  waves  that  dance 
And  wandering  loveliness.     He  leaves  a  white 

Unbroken  glory,  a  gathered  radiance, 
A  width,  a  shining  peace,  under  the  night. 

The  magic  words  bring  back  the  scene.  Again  we 
feel  Nature  drawing  close  to  us,  uniting  with  us,  till 
we  are  filled  with  the  gladness  of  the  waves  dancing  in 
the  sunshine,  with  the  awe  of  the  moonlight  on  the 
frozen  lake.  These  were  not  moments  when  we  fell 
below  ourselves.  We  do  not  look  back  on  them  and  say, 
"It  was  disgraceful  for  a  man  with  six  sober  senses  and 
a  scientific  understanding  to  let  himself  be  deluded  in 
that  way.  I  will  take  Lamb's  Hydrodynamics  with  me 
next  time".  It  is  good  that  there  should  be  such 
moments  for  us.  Life  would  be  stunted  and  narrow  if 
we  could  feel  no  significance  in  the  world  around  us 
beyond  that  which  can  be  weighed  and  measured  with 
the  tools  of  the  physicist  or  described  by  the  metrical 
symbols  of  the  mathematician. 

Of  course  it  was  an  illusion.  We  can  easily  expose 
the  rather  clumsy  trick  that  was  played  on  us.  Aethereal 
vibrations  of  various  wave-lengths,  reflected  at  different 
angles  from  the  disturbed  interface  between  air  and 
water,  reached  our  eyes,  and  by  photoelectric  action 
caused  appropriate  stimuli  to  travel  along  the  optic 
nerves  to  a  brain-centre.  Here  the  mind  set  to  work  to 
weave  an  impression  out  of  the  stimuli.  The  incoming 
material  was  somewhat  meagre;  but  the  mind  is  a  great 
storehouse  of  associations  that  could  be  used  to  clothe 


318  SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM 

the  skeleton.  Having  woven  an  impression  the  mind 
surveyed  all  that  it  had  made  and  decided  that  it  was 
very  good.  The  critical  faculty  was  lulled.  We  ceased 
to  analyse  and  were  conscious  only  of  the  impression 
as  a  whole.  The  warmth  of  the  air,  the  scent  of  the 
grass,  the  gentle  stir  of  the  breeze,  combined  with  the 
visual  scene  in  one  transcendent  impression,  around  us 
and  within  us.  Associations  emerging  from  their  store- 
house grew  bolder.  Perhaps  we  recalled  the  phrase 
"rippling  laughter".  Waves — ripples — laughter — glad- 
ness— the  ideas  jostled  one  another.  Quite  illogically  we 
were  glad;  though  what  there  can  possibly  be  to  be  glad 
about  in  a  set  of  aethereal  vibrations  no  sensible  person 
can  explain.  A  mood  of  quiet  joy  suffused  the  whole 
impression.  The  gladness  in  ourselves  was  in  Nature, 
in  the  waves,  everywhere.     That's  how  it  was. 

It  was  an  illusion.  Then  why  toy  with  it  longer? 
These  airy  fancies  which  the  mind,  when  we  do  not 
keep  it  severely  in  order,  projects  into  the  external  world 
should  be  of  no  concern  to  the  earnest  seeker  after  truth. 
Get  back  to  the  solid  substance  of  things,  to  the  material 
of  the  water  moving  under  the  pressure  of  the  wind  and 
the  force  of  gravitation  in  obedience  to  the  laws  of 
hydrodynamics.  But  the  solid  substance  of  things  is 
another  illusion.  It  too  is  a  fancy  projected  by  the  mind 
into  the  external  world.  We  have  chased  the  solid 
substance  from  the  continuous  liquid  to  the  atom,  from 
the  atom  to  the  electron,  and  there  we  have  lost  it.  But 
at  least,  it  will  be  said,  we  have  reached  something  real 
at  the  end  of  the  chase — the  protons  and  electrons.  Or 
if  the  new  quantum  theory  condemns  these  images  as 
too  concrete  and  leaves  us  with  no  coherent  images  at 
all,  at  least  we  have  symbolic  co-ordinates  and  momenta 
and    Hamiltonian    functions    devoting    themselves    with 


SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM  319 

single-minded  purpose  to  ensuring  that  qp  —  pq  shall  be 
equal  to  ih/m. 

In  a  previous  chapter  I  have  tried  to  show  that  by 
following  this  course  we  reach  a  cyclic  scheme  which 
from  its  very  nature  can  only  be  a  partial  expression  of 
our  environment.  It  is  not  reality  but  the  skeleton  of 
reality.  "Actuality"  has  been  lost  in  the  exigencies  of 
the  chase.  Having  first  rejected  the  mind  as  a  worker 
of  illusion  we  have  in  the  end  to  return  to  the  mind  and 
say,  "Here  are  worlds  well  and  truly  built  on  a  basis 
more  secure  than  your  fanciful  illusions.  But  there  is 
nothing  to  make  any  one  of  them  an  actual  world. 
Please  choose  one  and  weave  your  fanciful  images  into 
it.  That  alone  can  make  it  actual".  We  have  torn  away 
the  mental  fancies  to  get  at  the  reality  beneath,  only  to 
find  that  the  reality  of  that  which  is  beneath  is  bound 
up  with  its  potentiality  of  awakening  these  fancies.  It 
is  because  the  mind,  the  weaver  of  illusion,  is  also  the 
only  guarantor  of  reality  that  reality  is  always  to  be 
sought  at  the  base  of  illusion.  Illusion  is  to  reality  as 
the  smoke  to  the  fire.  I  will  not  urge  that  hoary  un- 
truth "There  is  no  smoke  without  fire".  But  it  is 
reasonable  to  inquire  whether  in  the  mystical  illusions  of 
man  there  is  not  a  reflection  of  an  underlying  reality. 

To  put  a  plain  question — Why  should  it  be  good  for 
us  to  experience  a  state  of  self-deception  such  as  I  have 
described?  I  think  everyone  admits  that  it  is  good  to 
have  a  spirit  sensitive  to  the  influences  of  Nature,  good 
to  exercise  an  appreciative  imagination  and  not  always 
to  be  remorselessly  dissecting  our  environment  after 
the  manner  of  the  mathematical  physicists.  And  it  is 
good  not  merely  in  a  utilitarian  sense,  but  in  some 
purposive  sense  necessary  to  the  fulfilment  of  the  life 
that  is  given  us.     It  is  not  a  dope  which  it  is  expedient 


320  SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM 

to  take  from  time  to  time  so  that  we  may  return  with 
greater  vigour  to  the  more  legitimate  employment  of 
the  mind  in  scientific  investigation.  Just  possibly  it 
might  be  defended  on  the  ground  that  it  affords  to  the 
non-mathematical  mind  in  some  feeble  measure  that 
delight  in  the  external  world  which  would  be  more 
fully  provided  by  an  intimacy  with  its  differential 
equations.  (Lest  it  should  be  thought  that  I  have 
intended  to  pillory  hydrodynamics,  I  hasten  to  say  in 
this  connection  that  I  would  not  rank  the  intellectual 
(scientific)  appreciation  on  a  lower  plane  than  the 
mystical  appreciation;  and  I  know  of  passages  written 
in  mathematical  symbols  which  in  their  sublimity  might 
vie  with  Rupert  Brooke's  sonnet.)  But  I  think  you  will 
agree  with  me  that  it  is  impossible  to  allow  that  the  one 
kind  of  appreciation  can  adequately  fill  the  place  of  the 
other.  Then  how  can  it  be  deemed  good  if  there  is 
nothing  in  it  but  self-deception?  That  would  be  an 
upheaval  of  all  our  ideas  of  ethics.  It  seems  to  me  that 
the  only  alternatives  are  either  to  count  all  such  sur- 
render to  the  mystical  contact  of  Nature  as  mischievous 
and  ethically  wrong,  or  to  admit  that  in  these  moods 
we  catch  something  of  the  true  relation  of  the  world  to 
ourselves — a  relation  not  hinted  at  in  a  purely  scientific 
analysis  of  its  content.  I  think  the  most  ardent  material- 
ist does  not  advocate,  or  at  any  rate  does  not  practice, 
the  first  alternative;  therefore  I  assume  the  second  alter- 
native, that  there  is  some  kind  of  truth  at  the  base  of  the 
illusion. 

But  we  must  pause  to  consider  the  extent  of  the 
illusion.  Is  it  a  question  of  a  small  nugget  of  reality 
buried  under  a  mountain  of  illusion?  If  that  were  so  it 
would  be  our  duty  to  rid  our  minds  of  some  of  the 
illusion  at  least,  and  try  to  know  the  truth  in  purer  form. 


SYMBOLIC  AND  INTIMATE  KNOWLEDGE    321 

But  I  cannot  think  there  is  much  amiss  with  our  appre- 
ciation of  the  natural  scene  that  so  impresses  us.  I  do 
not  think  a  being  more  highly  endowed  than  ourselves 
would  prune  away  much  of  what  we  feel.  It  is  not  so 
much  that  the  feeling  itself  is  at  fault  as  that  our 
introspective  examination  of  it  wraps  it  in  fanciful 
imagery.  If  I  were  to  try  to  put  into  words  the  essen- 
tial truth  revealed  in  the  mystic  experience,  it  would  be 
that  our  minds  are  not  apart  from  the  world;  and  the 
feelings  that  we  have  of  gladness  and  melancholy  and 
our  yet  deeper  feelings  are  not  of  ourselves  alone,  but 
are  glimpses  of  a  reality  transcending  the  narrow  limits 
of  our  particular  consciousness — that  the  harmony  and 
beauty  of  the  face  of  Nature  is  at  root  one  with  the 
gladness  that  transfigures  the  face  of  man.  We  try  to 
express  much  the  same  truth  when  we  say  that  the 
physical  entities  are  only  an  extract  of  pointer  readings 
and  beneath  them  is  a  nature  continuous  with  our  own. 
But  I  do  not  willingly  put  it  into  words  or  subject  it  to 
introspection.  We  have  seen  how  in  the  physical  world 
the  meaning  is  greatly  changed  when  we  contemplate 
it  as  surveyed  from  without  instead  of,  as  it  essentially 
must  be,  from  within.  By  introspection  we  drag  out  the 
truth  for  external  survey;  but  in  the  mystical  feeling 
the  truth  is  apprehended  from  within  and  is,  as  it  should 
be,  a  part  of  ourselves. 

Symbolic  Knowledge  and  Intimate  Knowledge.  May  I 
elaborate  this  objection  to  introspection?  We  have  two 
kinds  of  knowledge  which  I  call  symbolic  knowledge 
and  intimate  knowledge.  I  do  not  know  whether  it 
would  be  correct  to  say  that  reasoning  is  only  applicable 
to  symbolic  knowledge,  but  the  more  customary  forms 
of  reasoning  have  been  developed   for  symbolic  know- 


322  SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM 

ledge  only.  The  intimate  knowledge  will  not  submit  to 
codification  and  analysis;  or,  rather,  when  we  attempt 
to  analyse  it  the  intimacy  is  lost  and  it  is  replaced  by 
symbolism. 

For  an  illustration  let  us  consider  Humour.  I  suppose 
that  humour  can  be  analysed  to  some  extent  and  the 
essential  ingredients  of  the  different  kinds  of  wit 
classified.  Suppose  that  we  are  offered  an  alleged  joke. 
We  subject  it  to  scientific  analysis  as  we  would  a  chemical 
salt  of  doubtful  nature,  and  perhaps  after  careful  con- 
sideration of  all  its  aspects  we  are  able  to  confirm  that 
it  really  and  truly  is  a  joke.  Logically,  I  suppose,  our 
next  procedure  would  be  to  laugh.  But  it  may  certainly 
be  predicted  that  as  the  result  of  this  scrutiny  we  shall 
have  lost  all  inclination  we  may  ever  have  had  to  laugh 
at  it.  It  simply  does  not  do  to  expose  the  inner  workings 
of  a  joke.  The  classification  concerns  a  symbolic  know- 
ledge of  humour  which  preserves  all  the  characteristics 
of  a  joke  except  its  laughableness.  The  real  appreciation 
must  come  spontaneously,  not  introspectively.  I  think 
this  is  a  not  unfair  analogy  for  our  mystical  feeling  for 
Nature,  and  I  would  venture  even  to  apply  it  to  our 
mystical  experience  of  God.  There  are  some  to  whom 
the  sense  of  a  divine  presence  irradiating  the  soul  is  one 
of  the  most  obvious  things  of  experience.  In  their  view 
a  man  without  this  sense  is  to  be  regarded  as  we  regard 
a  man  without  a  sense  of  humour.  The  absence  is  a  kind 
of  mental  deficiency.  We  may  try  to  analyse  the  ex- 
perience as  we  analyse  humour,  and  construct  a  theology, 
or  it  may  be  an  atheistic  philosophy,  which  shall  put 
into  scientific  form  what  is  to  be  inferred  about  it.  But 
let  us  not  forget  that  the  theology  is  symbolic  knowledge 
whereas  the  experience  is  intimate  knowledge.  And  as 
laughter  cannot  be  compelled  by  the  scientific  exposition 


DEFENCE  OF  MYSTICISM  323 

of  the  structure  of  a  joke,  so  a  philosophic  discussion 
of  the  attributes  of  God  (or  an  impersonal  substitute) 
is  likely  to  miss  the  intimate  response  of  the  spirit  which 
is  the  central  point  of  the  religious  experience. 

Defence  of  Mysticism.  A  defence  of  the  mystic  might 
run  something  like  this.  We  have  acknowledged  that  the 
entities  of  physics  can  from  their  very  nature  form  only 
a  partial  aspect  of  the  reality.  How  are  we  to  deal  with 
the  other  part?  It  cannot  be  said  that  that  other  part 
concerns  us  less  than  the  physical  entities.  Feelings, 
purpose,  values,  make  up  our  consciousness  as  much  as 
sense-impressions.  We  follow  up  the  sense-impressions 
and  find  that  they  lead  into  an  external  world  discussed 
by  science;  we  follow  up  the  other  elements  of  our 
being  and  find  that  they  lead — not  into  a  world  of  space 
and  time,  but  surely  somewhere.  If  you  take  the  view 
that  the  whole  of  consciousness  is  reflected  in  the  dance 
of  electrons  in  the  brain,  so  that  each  emotion  is  a 
separate  figure  of  the  dance,  then  all  features  of  con- 
sciousness alike  lead  into  the  external  world  of  physics. 
But  I  assume  that  you  have  followed  me  in  rejecting 
this  view,  and  that  you  agree  that  consciousness  as  a 
whole  is  greater  than  those  quasi-metrical  aspects  of  it 
which  are  abstracted  to  compose  the  physical  brain. 
We  have  then  to  deal  with  those  parts  of  our  being 
unamenable  to  metrical  specification,  that  do  not  make 
contact — jut  out,  as  it  were — into  space  and  time.  By 
dealing  with  them  I  do  not  mean  make  scientific  in- 
quiry into  them.  The  first  step  is  to  give  acknowledged 
status  to  the  crude  conceptions  in  which  the  mind  invests 
them,  similar  to  the  status  of  those  crude  conceptions 
which  constitute  the  familiar  material  world. 

Our  conception  of  the  familiar  table  was  an  illusion. 


324  SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM 

But  if  some  prophetic  voice  had  warned  us  that  it  was 
an  illusion  and  therefore  we  had  not  troubled  to  investi- 
gate further  we  should  never  have  found  the  scientific 
table.  To  reach  the  reality  of  the  table  we  need  to  be 
endowed  with  sense-organs  to  weave  images  and  illusions 
about  it.  And  so  it  seems  to  me  that  the  first  step  in  a 
broader  revelation  to  man  must  be  the  awakening  of 
image-building  in  connection  with  the  higher  faculties 
of  his  nature,  so  that  these  are  no  longer  blind  alleys 
but  open  out  into  a  spiritual  world — a  world  partly  of 
illusion,  no  doubt,  but  in  which  he  lives  no  less  than  in 
the  world,  also  of  illusion,  revealed  by  the  senses. 

The  mystic,  if  haled  before  a  tribunal  of  scientists, 
might  perhaps  end  his  defence  on  this  note.  He  would 
say,  The  familiar  material  world  of  everyday  conception, 
though  lacking  somewhat  in  scientific  truth,  is  good 
enough  to  live  in;  in  fact  the  scientific  world  of  pointer 
readings  would  be  an  impossible  sort  of  place  to  inhabit. 
It  is  a  symbolic  world  and  the  only  thing  that  could  live 
comfortably  in  it  would  be  a  symbol.  But  I  am  not 
a  symbol;  I  am  compounded  of  that  mental  activity 
which  is  from  your  point  of  view  a  nest  of  illusion,  so 
that  to  accord  with  my  own  nature  I  have  to  transform 
even  the  world  explored  by  my  senses.  But  I  am  not 
merely  made  up  of  senses;  the  rest  of  my  nature  has  to 
live  and  grow.  I  have  to  render  account  of  that  environ- 
ment into  which  it  has  its  outlet.  My  conception  of 
my  spiritual  environment  is  not  to  be  compared  with 
your  scientific  world  of  pointer  readings;  it  is  an  every- 
day world  to  be  compared  with  the  material  world  of 
familiar  experience.  I  claim  it  as  no  more  real  and  no 
less  real  than  that.  Primarily  it  is  not  a  world  to  be 
analysed,  but  a  world  to  be  lived  in." 

Granted    that    this    takes    us    outside    the    sphere    of 


DEFENCE  OF  MYSTICISM  325 

exact  knowledge,  and  that  it  is  difficult  to  imagine  that 
anything  corresponding  to  exact  science  will  ever  be 
applicable  to  this  part  of  our  environment,  the  mystic 
is  unrepentant.  Because  we  are  unable  to  render  exact 
account  of  our  environment  it  does  not  follow  that  it 
would  be  better  to  pretend  that  we  live  in  a  vacuum. 

If  the  defence  may  be  considered  to  have  held  good 
against  the  first  onslaught,  perhaps  the  next  stage  of  the 
attack  will  be  an  easy  tolerance.  "Very  well.  Have  it 
your  own  way.  It  is  a  harmless  sort  of  belief — not  like 
a  more  dogmatic  theology.  You  want  a  sort  of  spiritual 
playground  for  those  queer  tendencies  in  man's  nature, 
which  sometimes  take  possession  of  him.  Run  away 
and  play  then;  but  do  not  bother  the  serious  people  who 
are  making  the  world  go  round."  The  challenge  now 
comes  not  from  the  scientific  materialism  which  pro- 
fesses to  seek  a  natural  explanation  of  spiritual  power, 
but  from  the  deadlier  moral  materialism  which  despises 
it.  Few  deliberately  hold  the  philosophy  that  the  forces 
of  progress  are  related  only  to  the  material  side  of  our 
environment,  but  few  can  claim  that  they  are  not  more 
or  less  under  its  sway.  We  must  not  interrupt  the 
"practical  men",  these  busy  moulders  of  history  carry- 
ing us  at  ever-increasing  pace  towards  our  destiny  as 
an  ant-heap  of  humanity  infesting  the  earth.  But  is  it 
true  in  history  that  material  forces  have  been  the 
most  potent  factors?  Call  it  of  God,  of  the  Devil, 
fanaticism,  unreason;  but  do  not  underrate  the  power  of 
the  mystic.  Mysticism  may  be  fought  as  error  or  believed 
as  inspired,  but  it  is  no  matter  for  easy  tolerance — 

We  are  the  music-makers 

And   we   are   the   dreamers   of    dreams 

Wandering  by  lone  sea-breakers 
And  sitting  by  desolate  streams ; 


326  SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM 

World-losers  and  world-forsakers, 

On  whom  the  pale  moon  gleams: 
Yet  we  are  the  movers  and  shakers 

Of  the  world  for  ever,  it  seems. 

Reality  and  Mysticism,  But  a  defence  before  the  scien- 
tists may  not  be  a  defence  to  our  own  self-questionings. 
We  are  haunted  by  the  word  reality.  I  have  already  tried 
to  deal  with  the  questions  which  arise  as  to  the  meaning 
of  reality;  but  it  presses  on  us  so  persistently  that,  at  the 
risk  of  repetition,  I  must  consider  it  once  more  from 
the  standpoint  of  religion.  A  compromise  of  illusion 
and  reality  may  be  all  very  well  in  our  attitude  towards 
physical  surroundings;  but  to  admit  such  a  compromise 
into  religion  would  seem  to  be  a  trifling  with  sacred 
things.  Reality  seems  to  concern  religious  beliefs  much 
more  than  any  others.  No  one  bothers  as  to  whether 
there  is  a  reality  behind  humour.  The  artist  who  tries 
to  bring  out  the  soul  in  his  picture  does  not  really  care 
whether  and  in  what  sense  the  soul  can  be  said  to  exist. 
Even  the  physicist  is  unconcerned  as  to  whether  atoms 
or  electrons  really  exist;  he  usually  asserts  that  they  do, 
but,  as  we  have  seen,  existence  is  there  used  in  a 
domestic  sense  and  no  inquiry  is  made  as  to  whether 
it  is  more  than  a  conventional  term.  In  most  subjects 
(perhaps  not  excluding  philosophy)  it  seems  sufficient 
to  agree  on  the  things  that  we  shall  call  real,  and  after- 
wards try  to  discover  what  we  mean  by  the  word.  And 
so  it  comes  about  that  religion  seems  to  be  the  one  field 
of  inquiry  in  which  the  question  of  reality  and  existence 
is  treated  as  of  serious  and  vital  importance. 

But  it  is  difficult  to  see  how  such  an  inquiry  can  be 
profitable.  When  Dr.  Johnson  felt  himself  getting  tied 
up  in  argument  over  "Bishop  Berkeley's  ingenious 
sophistry  to  prove  the  non-existence  of  matter,  and  that 


REALITY  AND  MYSTICISM  327 

everything  in  the  universe  is  merely  ideal",  he  answered, 
"striking  his  foot  with  mighty  force  against  a  large 
stone,  till  he  rebounded  from  it, — 'I  refute  it  thus*  ". 
Just  what  that  action  assured  him  of  is  not  very  obvious; 
but  apparently  he  found  it  comforting.  And  to-day  the 
matter-of-fact  scientist  feels  the  same  impulse  to  recoil 
from  these  flights  of  thought  back  to  something  kick- 
able,  although  he  ought  to  be  aware  by  this  time  that 
what  Rutherford  has  left  us  of  the  large  stone  is  scarcely 
worth  kicking. 

There  is  still  the  tendency  to  use  "reality"  as  a  word 
of  magic  comfort  like  the  blessed  word  "Mesopotamia". 
If  I  were  to  assert  the  reality  of  the  soul  or  of  God, 
I  should  certainly  not  intend  a  comparison  with 
Johnson's  large  stone — a  patent  illusion — or  even  with 
the  p's  and  qs  of  the  quantum  theory — an  abstract 
symbolism.  Therefore  I  have  no  right  to  use  the  word 
in  religion  for  the  purpose  of  borrowing  on  its  behalf 
that  comfortable  feeling  which  (probably  wrongly)  has 
become  associated  with  stones  and  quantum  co-ordi- 
nates. 

Scientific  instincts  warn  me  that  any  attempt  to 
answer  the  question  "What  is  real?"  in  a  broader  sense 
than  that  adopted  for  domestic  purposes  in  science,  is 
likely  to  lead  to  a  floundering  among  vain  words  and 
high-sounding  epithets.  We  all  know  that  there  are 
regions  of  the  human  spirit  untrammelled  by  the  world 
of  physics.  In  the  mystic  sense  of  the  creation  around 
us,  in  the  expression  of  art,  in  a  yearning  towards  God, 
the  soul  grows  upward  and  finds  the  fulfilment  of 
something  implanted  in  its  nature.  The  sanction  for 
this  development  is  within  us,  a  striving  born  with  our 
consciousness  or  an  Inner  Light  proceeding  from  a 
greater  power  than  ours.     Science  can  scarcely  question 


328  SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM 

this  sanction,  for  the  pursuit  of  science  springs  from  a 
striving  which  the  mind  is  impelled  to  follow,  a  ques- 
tioning that  will  not  be  suppressed.  Whether  in  the 
intellectual  pursuits  of  science  or  in  the  mystical  pur- 
suits of  the  spirit,  the  light  beckons  ahead  and  the 
purpose  surging  in  our  nature  responds.  Can  we  not 
leave  it  at  that?  Is  it  really  necessary  to  drag  in  the 
comfortable  word  "reality"  to  be  administered  like  a 
pat  on  the  back? 

The  problem  of  the  scientific  world  is  part  of  a 
broader  problem — the  problem  of  all  experience.  Ex- 
perience may  be  regarded  as  a  combination  of  self 
and  environment,  it  being  part  of  the  problem  to 
disentangle  these  two  interacting  components.  Life, 
religion,  knowledge,  truth  are  all  involved  in  this 
problem,  some  relating  to  the  finding  of  ourselves,  some 
to  the  finding  of  our  environment  from  the  experience 
confronting  us.  All  of  us  in  our  lives  have  to  make 
something  of  this  problem;  and  it  is  an  important 
condition  that  we  who  have  to  solve  the  problem  are 
ourselves  part  of  the  problem.  Looking  at  the  very 
beginning,  the  initial  fact  is  the  feeling  of  purpose  in 
ourselves  which  urges  us  to  embark  on  the  problem. 
We  are  meant  to  fulfil  something  by  our  lives.  There 
are  faculties  with  which  we  are  endowed,  or  which  we 
ought  to  attain,  which  must  find  a  status  and  an  outlet 
in  the  solution.  It  may  seem  arrogant  that  we  should  in 
this  way  insist  on  moulding  truth  to  our  own  nature; 
but  it  is  rather  that  the  problem  of  truth  can  only  spring 
from  a  desire  for  truth  which  is  in  our  nature. 

A  rainbow  described  in  the  symbolism  of  physics  is 
a  band  of  aethereal  vibrations  arranged  in  systematic 
order  of  wave-length  from  about  -000040  cm.  to 
•000072  cm.     From  one  point  of  view  we  are  paltering 


SIGNIFICANCE  AND  VALUES  329 

with  the  truth  whenever  we  admire  the  gorgeous  bow 
of  colour,  and  should  strive  to  reduce  our  minds  to  such 
a  state  that  we  receive  the  same  impression  from  the 
rainbow  as  from  a  table  of  wave-lengths.  But  although 
that  is  how  the  rainbow  impresses  itself  on  an  impersonal 
spectroscope,  we  are  not  giving  the  whole  truth  and 
significance  of  experience — the  starting-point  of  the 
problem — if  we  suppress  the  factors  wherein  we  our- 
selves differ  from  a  spectroscope.  We  cannot  say  that 
the  rainbow,  as  part  of  the  world,  was  meant  to  convey 
the  vivid  effects  of  colour;  but  we  can  perhaps  say  that 
the  human  mind  as  part  of  the  world  was  meant  to 
perceive  it  that  way. 

Significance  and  Values.  When  we  think  of  the  sparkling 
waves  as  moved  with  laughter  we  are  evidently  attri- 
buting a  significance  to  the  scene  which  was  not  there. 
The  physical  elements  of  the  water — the  scurrying 
electric  charges — were  guiltless  of  any  intention  to 
convey  the  impression  that  they  were  happy.  But  so 
also  were  they  guiltless  of  any  intention  to  convey  the 
impression  of  substance,  of  colour,  or  of  geometrical 
form  of  the  waves.  If  they  can  be  held  to  have  had  any 
intention  at  all  it  was  to  satisfy  certain  differential 
equations — and  that  was  because  they  are  the  creatures 
of  the  mathematician  who  has  a  partiality  for  differential 
equations.  The  physical  no  less  than  the  mystical 
significance  of  the  scene  is  not  there;  it  is  here — in  the 
mind. 

What  we  make  of  the  world  must  be  largely  de- 
pendent on  the  sense-organs  that  we  happen  to  possess. 
How  the  world  must  have  changed  since  man  came  to 
rely  on  his  eyes  rather  than  his  nose !  You  are  alone  on 
the  mountains  wrapt  in  a  great  silence ;  but  equip  yourself 


330  SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM 

with  an  extra  artificial  sense-organ  and,  lo!  the  aether  is 
hideous  with  the  blare  of  the  Savoy  bands.     Or — 

The  isle  is  full  of  noises, 
Sounds,  and  sweet  airs,  that  give  delight,  and  hurt  not. 
Sometimes  a  thousand  twangling  instruments 
Will  hum  about  mine  ears ;  and  sometimes  voices. 

So   far   as   broader   characteristics   are   concerned  wc 
see  in  Nature  what  we  look  for  or  are  equipped  to  look 
for.     Of  course,  I  do  not  mean  that  we  can  arrange  the 
details  of  the  scene;  but  by  the  light  and  shade  of  our 
values  we  can  bring  out  things  that  shall  have  the  broad 
characteristics  we  esteem.     In  this  sense  the  value  placed 
on  permanence  creates  the  world  of  apparent  substance; 
in  this  sense,  perhaps,  the  God  within  creates  the  God 
in  Nature.     But  no  complete  view  can  be  obtained  so 
long  as  we  separate  our  consciousness  from  the  world 
of  which  it  is  a  part.     We  can  only  speak  speculatively 
of   that  which   I   have   called   the   "background  of   the 
pointer  readings";  but  it  would  at  least  seem  plausible 
that  if  the  values  which  give  the  light  and  shade  of  the 
world  are  absolute  they  must  belong  to  the  background, 
unrecognised    in   physics    because    they    are    not    in    the 
pointer  readings  but  recognised  by  consciousness  which 
has  its  roots  in  the  background.     I  have  no  wish  to  put 
that  forward  as  a  theory;  it  is  only  to  emphasise  that, 
limited  as  we  are  to  a  knowledge  of  the  physical  world 
and  its  points  of  contact  with  the  background  in  isolated 
consciousness,   we   do   not  quite   attain   that  thought  of 
the  unity  of  the  whole  which  is  essential  to  a  complete 
theory.     Presumably  human  nature  has  been  specialised 
to    a    considerable    extent   by   the    operation    of   natural 
selection;    and    it    might    well    be    debated   whether    its 
valuation  of  permanence  and  other  traits  now  apparently 


SIGNIFICANCE  AND  VALUES  331 

fundamental  are  essential  properties  of  consciousness  or 
have  been  evolved  through  interplay  with  the  external 
world.  In  that  case  the  values  given  by  mind  to  the 
external  world  have  originally  come  to  it  from  the 
external  world-stuff.  Such  a  tossing  to  and  fro  of  values 
is,  I  think,  not  foreign  to  our  view  that  the  world-stuff 
behind  the  pointer  readings  is  of  nature  continuous  with 
the  mind. 

In  viewing  the  world  in  a  practical  way  values  for 
normal  human  consciousness  may  be  taken  as  standard. 
But  the  evident  possibility  of  arbitrariness  in  this 
valuation  sets  us  hankering  after  a  standard  that  could 
be  considered  final  and  absolute.  We  have  two  alter- 
natives. Either  there  are  no  absolute  values,  so  that  the 
sanctions  of  the  inward  monitor  in  our  consciousness  are 
the  final  court  of  appeal  beyonu  which  it  is  idle  to  in- 
quire. Or  there  are  absolute  values;  then  we  can  only 
trust  optimistically  that  our  values  are  some  pale 
reflection  of  those  of  the  Absolute  Valuer,  or  that  we 
have  insight  into  the  mind  of  the  Absolute  from  whence 
come  those  strivings  and  sanctions  whose  authority  we 
usually  forbear  to  question. 

I  have  naturally  tried  to  make  the  outlook  reached  in 
these  lectures  as  coherent  as  possible,  but  I  should  not 
be  greatly  concerned  if  under  the  shafts  of  criticism  it 
becomes  very  ragged.  Coherency  goes  with  finality; 
and  the  anxious  question  is  whether  our  arguments  have 
begun  right  rather  than  whether^  they  have  had  the  good 
fortune  to  end  right.  The  leading  points  which  have 
seemed  to  me  to  deserve  philosophic  consideration  may 
be  summarised  as  follows: 

(1)  The  symbolic  nature  of  the  entities  of  physics 
is  generally  recognised;  and  the  scheme  of  physics  is 
now  formulated  in  such  a  way  as  to  make  it  almost 


332  SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM 

self-evident    that    it   is    a   partial    aspect    of    something 
wider. 

(2)  Strict  causality  is  abandoned  in  the  material 
world.  Our  ideas  of  the  controlling  laws  are  in  process 
of  reconstruction  and  it  is  not  possible  to  predict  what 
kind  of  form  they  will  ultimately  take;  but  all  the  in- 
dications are  that  strict  causality  has  dropped  out 
permanently.  This  relieves  the  former  necessity  of 
supposing  that  mind  is  subject  to  deterministic  law  or 
alternatively  that  it  can  suspend  deterministic  law  in  the 
material  world. 

(3)  Recognising  that  the  physical  world  is  entirely 
abstract  and  without  "actuality"  apart  from  its  linkage 
to  consciousness,  we  restore  consciousness  to  the  funda- 
mental position  instead  of  representing  it  as  an  in- 
essential complication  occasionally  found  in  the  midst 
of  inorganic  nature  at  a  late  stage  of  evolutionary 
history. 

(4)  The  sanction  for  correlating  a  "real"  physical 
world  to  certain  feelings  of  which  we  are  conscious  does 
not  seem  to  differ  in  any  essential  respect  from  the 
sanction  for  correlating  a  spiritual  domain  to  another 
side  of  our  personality. 

It  is  not  suggested  that  there  is  anything  new  in  this 
philosophy.  In  particular  the  essence  of  the  first  point 
has  been  urged  by  many  writers,  and  has  no  doubt  won 
individual  assent  from  many  scientists  before  the  recent 
revolutions  of  physical  theory.  But  it  places  a  somewhat 
different  complexion  on  the  matter  when  this  is  not 
merely  a  philosophic  doctrine  to  which  intellectual 
assent  might  be  given,  but  has  become  part  of  the 
scientific  attitude  of  the  day,  illustrated  in  detail  in  the 
current  scheme  of  physics. 


CONVICTION  333 

Conviction.  Through  fourteen  chapters  you  have  fol- 
lowed with  me  the  scientific  approach  to  knowledge. 
I  have  given  the  philosophical  reflections  as  they  have 
naturally  arisen  from  the  current  scientific  conclusions, 
I  hope  without  distorting  them  for  theological  ends.  In 
the  present  chapter  the  standpoint  has  no  longer  been 
predominantly  scientific;  I  started  from  that  part  of  our 
experience  which  is  not  within  the  scope  of  a  scientific 
survey,  or  at  least  is  such  that  the  methods  of  physical 
science  would  miss  the  significance  that  we  consider  it 
essential  to  attribute  to  it.  The  starting-point  of  belief 
in  mystical  religion  is  a  conviction  of  significance  or, 
as  I  have  called  it  earlier,  the  sanction  of  a  striving  in 
the  consciousness.  This  must  be  emphasised  because 
appeal  to  intuitive  conviction  of  this  kind  has  been  the 
foundation  of  religion  through  all  ages  and  I  do  not 
wish  to  give  the  impression  that  we  have  now  found 
something  new  and  more  scientific  to  substitute.  I  re- 
pudiate the  idea  of  proving  the  distinctive  beliefs  of 
religion  either  from  the  data  of  physical  science  or  by 
the  methods  of  physical  science.  Presupposing  a 
mystical  religion  based  not  on  science  but  (rightly  or 
wrongly)  on  a  self-known  experience  accepted  as  fun- 
damental, we  can  proceed  to  discuss  the  various  criti- 
cisms which  science  might  bring  against  it  or  the 
possible  conflict  with  scientific  views  of  the  nature  of 
experience  equally  originating  from  self-known  data. 

It  is  necessary  to  examine  further  the  nature  of  the 
conviction  from  which  religion  arises;  otherwise  we  may 
seem  to  be  countenancing  a  blind  rejection  of  reason  as 
a  guide  to  truth.  There  is  a  hiatus  in  reasoning,  we  must 
admit;  but  it  is  scarcely  to  be  described  as  a  rejection 
of  reasoning.  There  is  just  the  same  hiatus  in  reasoning 
about  the  physical  world  if  we  go  back  far  enough.     We 


334  SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM 

can  only  reason  from  data  and  the  ultimate  data  must 
be  given  to  us  by  a  non-reasoning  process — a  self- 
knowledge  of  that  which  is  in  our  consciousness.  To 
make  a  start  we  must  be  aware  of  something.  But  that 
is  not  sufficient;  we  must  be  convinced  of  the  signifi- 
cance of  that  awareness.  We  are  bound  to  claim  for 
human  nature  that,  either  of  itself  or  as  inspired  by  a 
power  beyond,  it  is  capable  of  making  legitimate 
judgments  of  significance.  Otherwise  we  cannot  even 
reach  a  physical  world.* 

Accordingly  the  conviction  which  we  postulate  is 
that  certain  states  of  awareness  in  consciousness  have 
at  least  equal  significance  with  those  which  are  called 
sensations.  It  is  perhaps  not  irrelevant  to  note  that  time 
by  its  dual  entry  into  our  minds  (p.  51)  to  some  extent 
bridges  the  gap  between  sense-impressions  and  these 
other  states  of  awareness.  Amid  the  latter  must  be 
found  the  basis  of  experience  from  which  a  spiritual 
religion  arises.  The  conviction  is  scarcely  a  matter  to 
be  argued  about,  it  is  dependent  on  the  forcefulness  of 
the  feeling  of  awareness. 

But,  it  may  be  said,  although  we  may  have  such  a 
department  of  consciousness,  may  we  not  have  mis- 
understood altogether  the  nature  of  that  which  we 
believe  we  are  experiencing?  That  seems  to  me  to  be 
rather  beside  the  point.  In  regard  to  our  experience  of 
the  physical  world  we  have  very  much  misunderstood 
the  meaning  of  our  sensations.  It  has  been  the  task  of 
science  to  discover  that  things  are  very  different   from 

*  We  can  of  course  solve  the  problem  arising  from  certain  data 
without  being  convinced  of  the  significance  of  the  data — the  "official" 
scientific  attitude  as  I  have  previously  called  it  But  a  physical  world 
which  has  only  the  status  of  the  solution  of  a  problem,  arbitrarily  chosen 
to  pass  an  idle  hour,  is  not  what  is  intended  here. 


CONVICTION  335 

what  they  seem.  But  we  do  not  pluck  out  our  eyes 
because  they  persist  in  deluding  us  with  fanciful 
colourings  instead  of  giving  us  the  plain  truth  about 
wave-length.  It  is  in  the  midst  of  such  misrepresenta- 
tions of  environment  (if  you  must  call  them  so)  that  we 
have  to  live.  It  is,  however,  a  very  one-sided  view  of 
truth  which  can  find  in  the  glorious  colouring  of  our 
surroundings  nothing  but  misrepresentation — which 
takes  the  environment  to  be  all  important  and  the 
conscious  spirit  to  be  inessential.  In  our  scientific 
chapters  we  have  seen  how  the  mind  must  be  regarded 
as  dictating  the  course  of  world-building;  without  it 
there  is  but  formless  chaos.  It  is  the  aim  of  physical 
science,  so  far  as  its  scope  extends,  to  lay  bare  the 
fundamental  structure  underlying  the  world;  but  science 
has  also  to  explain  if  it  can,  or  else  humbly  to  accept, 
the  fact  that  from  this  world  have  arisen  minds  capable 
of  transmuting  the  bare  structure  into  the  richness  of 
our  experience.  It  is  not  misrepresentation  but  rather 
achievement — the  result  perhaps  of  long  ages  of  bio- 
logical evolution — that  we  should  have  fashioned  a 
familiar  world  out  of  the  crude  basis.  It  is  a  fulfilment 
of  the  purpose  of  man's  nature.  If  likewise  the  spiritual 
world  has  been  transmuted  by  a  religious  colour  beyond 
anything  implied  in  its  bare  external  qualities,  it  may 
be  allowable  to  assert  with  equal  conviction  that  this 
is  not  misrepresentation  but  the  achievement  of  a  divine 
element  in  man's  nature. 

May  I  revert  again  to  the  analogy  of  theology  with 
the  supposed  science  of  humour  which  (after  consulta- 
tion with  a  classical  authority)  I  venture  to  christen 
"geloeology".  Analogy  is  not  convincing  argument,  but 
it  must  serve  here.  Consider  the  proverbial  Scotchman 
with  strong  leanings  towards  philosophy  and  incapable 


336  SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM 

of  seeing  a  joke.  There  is  no  reason  why  he  should  not 
take  high  honours  in  geloeology,  and  for  example  write 
an  acute  analysis  of  the  differences  between  British  and 
American  humour.  His  comparison  of  our  respective 
jokes  would  be  particularly  unbiased  and  judicial,  seeing 
that  he  is  quite  incapable  of  seeing  the  point  of  either. 
But  it  would  be  useless  to  consider  his  views  as  to  which 
was  following  the  right  development;  for  that  he  would 
need  a  sympathetic  understanding — he  would  (in  the 
phrase  appropriate  to  the  other  side  of  my  analogy)  need 
to  be  converted.  The  kind  of  help  and  criticism  given 
by  the  geloeologist  and  the  philosophical  theologian  is 
to  secure  that  there  is  method  in  our  madness.  The 
former  may  show  that  our  hilarious  reception  of  a 
speech  is  the  result  of  a  satisfactory  dinner  and  a  good 
cigar  rather  than  a  subtle  perception  of  wit;  the  latter 
may  show  that  the  ecstatic  mysticism  of  the  anchorite 
is  the  vagary  of  a  fevered  body  and  not  a  transcendent 
revelation.  But  I  do  not  think  we  should  appeal  to 
either  of  them  to  discuss  the  reality  of  the  sense  with 
which  we  claim  to  be  endowed,  nor  the  direction  of  its 
right  development.  That  is  a  matter  for  our  inner  sense 
of  values  which  we  all  believe  in  to  some  extent,  though 
it  may  be  a  matter  of  dispute  just  how  far  it  goes.  If  we 
have  no  such  sense  then  it  would  seem  that  not  only 
religion,  but  the  physical  world  and  all  faith  in  reasoning 
totter  in  insecurity. 

I  have  sometimes  been  asked  whether  science  cannot 
now  furnish  an  argument  which  ought  to  convince  any 
reasonable  atheist.  I  could  no  more  ram  religious  con- 
viction into  an  atheist  than  I  could  ram  a  joke  into  the 
Scotchman.  The  only  hope  of  "converting"  the  latter 
is  that  through  contact  with  merry-minded  companions 
he   may  begin  to  realise   that   he   is   missing  something 


CONVICTION  337 

in  life  which  is  worth  attaining.  Probably  in  the  recesses 
of  his  solemn  mind  there  exists  inhibited  the  seed  of 
humour,  awaiting  an  awakening  by  such  an  impulse. 
The  same  advice  would  seem  to  apply  to  the  propagation 
of  religion;  it  has,  I  believe,  the  merit  of  being  entirely 
orthodox  advice. 

We  cannot  pretend  to  offer  proofs.  Proof  is  an  idol 
before  whom  the  pure  mathematician  tortures  himself. 
In  physics  we  are  generally  content  to  sacrifice  before 
the  lesser  shrine  of  Plausibility.  And  even  the  pure 
mathematician — that  stern  logician — reluctantly  allows 
himself  some  prejudgments;  he  is  never  quite  convinced 
that  the  scheme  of  mathematics  is  flawless,  and  mathe- 
matical logic  has  undergone  revolutions  as  profound  as 
the  revolutions  of  physical  theory.  We  are  all  alike 
stumblingly  pursuing  an  ideal  beyond  our  reach.  In 
science  we  sometimes  have  convictions  as  to  the  right 
solution  of  a  problem  which  we  cherish  but  cannot 
justify;  we  are  influenced  by  some  innate  sense  of  the 
fitness  of  things.  So  too  there  may  come  to  us  convic- 
tions in  the  spiritual  sphere  which  our  nature  bids  us 
hold  to.  I  have  given  an  example  of  one  such  conviction 
which  is  rarely  if  ever  disputed — that  surrender  to  the 
mystic  influence  of  a  scene  of  natural  beauty  is  right  and 
proper  for  a  human  spirit,  although  it  would  have  been 
deemed  an  unpardonable  eccentricity  in  the  "observer" 
contemplated  in  earlier  chapters.  Religious  conviction 
is  often  described  in  somewhat  analogous  terms  as  a 
surrender;  it  is  not  to  be  enforced  by  argument  on  those 
who  do  not  feel  its  claim  in  their  own  nature. 

I  think  it  is  inevitable  that  these  convictions  should 
emphasise  a  personal  aspect  of  what  we  are  trying  to 
grasp.  We  have  to  build  the  spiritual  world  out  of 
symbols  taken  from  our  own  personality,   as  we   build 


338  SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM 

the  scientific  world  out  of  the  metrical  symbols  of  the 
mathematician.  If  not,  it  can  only  be  left  ungraspable — 
an  environment  dimly  felt  in  moments  of  exaltation  but 
lost  to  us  in  the  sordid  routine  of  life.  To  turn  it  into 
more  continuous  channels  we  must  be  able  to  approach 
the  World-Spirit  in  the  midst  of  our  cares  and  duties  in 
that  simpler  relation  of  spirit  to  spirit  in  which  all  true 
religion  finds  expression. 

Mystical  Religion.  We  have  seen  that  the  cyclic  scheme 
of  physics  presupposes  a  background  outside  the  scope 
of  its  investigations.  In  this  background  we  must  find, 
first,  our  own  personality,  and  then  perhaps  a  greater 
personality.  The  idea  of  a  universal  Mind  or  Logos 
would  be,  I  think,  a  fairly  plausible  inference  from  the 
present  state  of  scientific  theory;  at  least  it  is  in  harmony 
with  it.  But  if  so,  all  that  our  inquiry  justifies  us  in  assert- 
ing is  a  purely  colourless  pantheism.  Science  cannot  tell 
whether  the  world-spirit  is  good  or  evil,  and  its  halting 
argument  for  the  existence  of  a  God  might  equally  well 
be  turned  into  an  argument  for  the  existence  of  a  Devil. 
I  think  that  that  is  an  example  of  the  limitation  of 
physical  schemes  that  has  troubled  us  before — namely, 
that  in  all  such  schemes  opposites  are  represented  by 
+  and  — .  Past  and  future,  cause  and  effect,  are  repre- 
sented in  this  inadequate  way.  One  of  the  greatest 
puzzles  of  science  is  to  discover  why  protons  and  elec- 
trons are  not  simply  the  opposites  of  one  another, 
although  our  whole  conception  of  electric  charge 
requires  that  positive  and  negative  electricity  should  be 
related  like  +  and  — .  The  direction  of  time's  arrow 
could  only  be  determined  by  that  incongruous  mixture 
of  theology  and  statistics  known  as  the  second  law  of 
thermodynamics;  or,  to  be  more  explicit,  the  direction 


MYSTICAL  RELIGION  339 

of  the  arrow  could  be  determined  by  statistical  rules, 
but  its  significance  as  a  governing  fact  "making  sense 
of  the  world'*  could  only  be  deduced  on  teleological 
assumptions.  If  physics  cannot  determine  which  way 
up  its  own  world  ought  to  be  regarded,  there  is  not  much 
hope  of  guidance  from  it  as  to  ethical  orientation.  We 
trust  to  some  inward  sense  of  fitness  when  we  orient  the 
physical  world  with  the  future  on  top,  and  likewise  we 
must  trust  to  some  inner  monitor  when  we  orient  the 
spiritual  world  with  the  good  on  top. 

Granted  that  physical  science  has  limited  its  scope 
so  as  to  leave  a  background  which  we  are  at  liberty  to, 
or  even  invited  to,  fill  with  a  reality  of  spiritual  import, 
we  have  yet  to  face  the  most  difficult  criticism  from 
science.  "Here",  says  science,  "I  have  left  a  domain 
in  which  I  shall  not  interfere.  I  grant  that  you  have 
some  kind  of  avenue  to  it  through  the  self-knowledge 
of  consciousness,  so  that  it  is  not  necessarily  a  domain 
of  pure  agnosticism.  But  how  are  you  going  to  deal  with 
this  domain?  Have  you  any  system  of  inference  from 
mystic  experience  comparable  to  the  system  by  which 
science  develops  a  knowledge  of  the  outside  world? 
I  do  not  insist  on  your  employing  my  method,  which 
I  acknowledge  is  inapplicable;  but  you  ought  to  have 
some  defensible  method.  The  alleged  b4sis  of  experience 
may  possibly  be  valid;  but  have  I  any  reason  to  regard 
the  religious  interpretation  currently  given  to  it  as 
anything  more  than  muddle-headed  romancing?" 

The  question  is  almost  beyond  my  scope.  I  can  only 
acknowledge  its  pertinency.  Although  I  have  chosen  the 
lightest  task  by  considering  only  mystical  religion — 
and  I  have  no  impulse  to  defend  any  other — I  am  not 
competent  to  give  an  answer  which  shall  be  anything 
like   complete.      It  is   obvious   that  the  insight   of  con- 


340  SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM 

sciousness,  although  the  only  avenue  to  what  I  have 
called  intimate  knowledge  of  the  reality  behind  the 
symbols  of  science,  is  not  to  be  trusted  implicitly 
without  control.  In  history  religious  mysticism  has 
often  been  associated  with  extravagances  that  cannot 
be  approved.  I  suppose  too  that  oversensitiveness  to 
aesthetic  influences  may  be  a  sign  of  a  neurotic  tem- 
perament unhealthy  to  the  individual.  We  must  allow 
something  for  the  pathological  condition  of  the  brain 
in  what  appear  to  be  moments  of  exalted  insight.  One 
begins  to  fear  that  after  all  our  faults  have  been  detected 
and  removed  there  will  not  be  any  "us"  left.  But  in 
the  study  of  the  physical  world  we  have  ultimately  to 
rely  on  our  sense-organs,  although  they  are  capable  of 
betraying  us  by  gross  illusions;  similarly  the  avenue  of 
consciousness  into  the  spiritual  world  may  be  beset  with 
pitfalls,  but  that  does  not  necessarily  imply  that  no 
advance  is  possible. 

A  point  that  must  be  insisted  on  is  that  religion  or 
contact  with  spiritual  power  if  it  has  any  general  im- 
portance at  all  must  be  a  commonplace  matter  of 
ordinary  life,  and  it  should  be  treated  as  such  in  any 
discussion.  I  hope  that  you  have  not  interpreted  my 
references  to  mysticism  as  referring  to  abnormal  experi- 
ences and  revelations.  I  am  not  qualified  to  discuss 
what  evidential  value  (if  any)  may  be  attached  to  the 
stranger  forms  of  experience  and  insight.  But  in  any 
case  to  suppose  that  mystical  religion  is  mainly  con- 
cerned with  these  is  like  supposing  that  Einstein's 
theory  is  mainly  concerned  with  the  perihelion  of 
Mercury  and  a  few  other  exceptional  observations. 
For  a  matter  belonging  to  daily  affairs  the  tone  of 
current  discussions  often  seems  quite  inappropriately 
pedantic. 


MYSTICAL  RELIGION  341 

As  scientists  we  realise  that  colour  is  merely  a  question 
of  the  wave-lengths  of  aethereal  vibrations;  but  that  does 
not  seem  to  have  dispelled  the  feeling  that  eyes  which 
reflect  light  near  wave-length  4800  are  a  subject  for 
rhapsody  whilst  those  which  reflect  wave-length  5300 
are  left  unsung.  We  have  not  yet  reached  the  practice  of 
the  Laputans,  who,  "if  they  would,  for  example,  praise  the 
beauty  of  a  woman,  or  any  other  animal,  they  describe 
it  by  rhombs,  circles,  parallelograms,  ellipses,  and  other 
geometrical  terms".  The  materialist  who  is  convinced 
that  all  phenomena  arise  from  electrons  and  quanta  and 
the  like  controlled  by  mathematical  formulae,  must 
presumably  hold  the  belief  that  his  wife  is  a  rather 
elaborate  differential  equation;  but  he  is  probably 
tactful  enough  not  to  obtrude  this  opinion  in  domestic 
life.  If  this  kind  of  scientific  dissection  is  felt  to  be 
inadequate  and  irrelevant  in  ordinary  personal  relation- 
ships, it  is  surely  out  of  place  in  the  most  personal 
relationship  of  all — that  of  the  human  soul  to  a  divine 
spirit. 

We  are  anxious  for  perfect  truth,  but  it  is  hard  to  say 
in  what  form  perfect  truth  is  to  be  found.  I  cannot 
quite  believe  that  it  has  the  form  typified  by  an  inventory. 
Somehow  as  part  of  its  perfection  there  should  be  in- 
corporated in  it  that  which  we  esteem  as  a  "sense  of 
proportion".  The  physicist  is  not  conscious  of  any 
disloyalty  to  truth  on  occasions  when  his  sense  of 
proportion  tells  him  to  regard  a  plank  as  continuous 
material,  well  knowing  that  it  is  "really"  empty  space 
containing  sparsely  scattered  electric  charges.  And  the 
deepest  philosophical  researches  as  to  the  nature  of  the 
Deity  may  give  a  conception  equally  out  of  proportion 
for  daily  life;  so  that  we  should  rather  employ  a  concep- 
tion that  was  unfolded  nearly  two  thousand  years  ago. 


342  SCIENCE  AND  MYSTICISM 

I  am  standing  on  the  threshold  about  to  enter  a  room. 
It  is  a  complicated  business.  In  the  first  place  I  must 
shove  against  an  atmosphere  pressing  with  a  force  of 
fourteen  pounds  on  every  square  inch  of  my  body. 
I  must  make  sure  of  landing  on  a  plank  travelling  at 
twenty  miles  a  second  round  the  sun — a  fraction  of  a 
second  too  early  or  too  late,  the  plank  would  be  miles 
away.  I  must  do  this  whilst  hanging  from  a  round 
planet  head  outward  into  space,  and  with  a  wind  of 
aether  blowing  at  no  one  knows  how  many  miles  a 
second  through  every  interstice  of  my  body.  The  plank 
has  no  solidity  of  substance.  To  step  on  it  is  like  stepping 
on  a  swarm  of  flies.  Shall  I  not  slip  through?  No,  if 
I  make  the  venture  one  of  the  flies  hits  me  and  gives  a 
boost  up  again;  I  fall  again  and  am  knocked  upwards 
by  another  fly;  and  so  on.  I  may  hope  that  the  net  result 
will  be  that  I  remain  about  steady;  but  if  unfortunately 
I  should  slip  through  the  floor  or  be  boosted  too  vio- 
lently up  to  the  ceiling,  the  occurrence  would  be,  not 
a  violation  of  the  laws  of  Nature,  but  a  rare  coincidence. 
These  are  some  of  the  minor  difficulties.  I  ought  really 
to  look  at  the  problem  four-dimensionally  as  concerning 
the  intersection  of  my  world-line  with  that  of  the  plank. 
Then  again  it  is  necessary  to  determine  in  which  direc- 
tion the  entropy  of  the  world  is  increasing  in  order  to 
make  sure  that  my  passage  over  the  threshold  is  an 
entrance,  not  an  exit. 

Verily,  it  is  easier  for  a  camel  to  pass  through  the  eye 
of  a  needle  than  for  a  scientific  man  to  pass  through  a 
door.  And  whether  the  door  be  barn  door  or  church 
door  it  might  be  wiser  that  he  should  consent  to  be  an 
ordinary  man  and  walk  in  rather  than  wait  till  all  the 
difficulties  involved  in  a  really  scientific  ingress  are 
resolved. 


"1 


CONCLUSION 

A  tide  of  indignation  has  been  surging  in  the  breast  of 
the  matter-of-fact  scientist  and  is  about  to  be  unloosed 
upon  us.  Let  us  broadly  survey  the  defence  we  can  set 
up. 

I  suppose  the  most  sweeping  charge  will  be  that  I 
have  been  talking  what  at  the  back  of  my  mind  I  must 
know  is  only  a  well-meaning  kind  of  nonsense.  I  can 
assure  you  that  there  is  a  scientific  part  of  me  that  has 
often  brought  that  criticism  during  some  of  the  later 
chapters.  I  will  not  say  that  I  have  been  half-convinced, 
but  at  least  I  have  felt  a  homesickness  for  the  paths  of 
physical  science  where  there  are  more  or  less  discernible 
handrails  to  keep  us  from  the  worst  morasses  of  foolish- 
ness. But  however  much  I  may  have  felt  inclined  to 
tear  up  this  part  of  the  discussion  and  confine  myself  to 
my  proper  profession  of  juggling  with  pointer  readings, 
I  find  myself  holding  to  the  main  principles.  Starting 
from  aether,  electrons  and  other  physical  machinery  we 
cannot  reach  conscious  man  and  render  count  of  what 
is  apprehended  in  his  consciousness.  Conceivably  we 
might  reach  a  human  machine  interacting  by  reflexes 
with  its  environment;  but  we  cannot  reach  rational  man 
morally  responsible  to  pursue  the  truth  as  to  aether  and 
electrons  or  to  religion.  Perhaps  it  may  seem  unneces- 
sarily portentous  to  invoke  the  latest  developments  of 
the  relativity  and  quantum  theories  merely  to  tell  you 
this;  but  that  is  scarcely  the  point.  We  have  followed 
these  theories  because  they  contain  the  conceptions  of 
modern  science;  and  it  is  not  a  question  of  asserting  a 
faith  that  science  must  ultimately  be  reconcilable  with 
an  idealistic  view,  but  of  examining  how  at  the  moment 

343 


344  CONCLUSION 

it  actually  stands  in  regard  to  it.  I  might  sacrifice  the 
detailed  arguments  of  the  last  four  chapters  (perhaps 
marred  by  dialectic  entanglement)  if  I  could  otherwise 
convey  the  significance  of  the  recent  change  which  has 
overtaken  scientific  ideals.  The  physicist  now  regards 
his  own  external  world  in  a  way  which  I  can  only  describe 
as  more  mystical,  though  not  less  exact  and  practical, 
than  that  which  prevailed  some  years  ago,  when  it  was 
taken  for  granted  that  nothing  could  be  true  unless  an 
engineer  could  make  a  model  of  it.  There  was  a  time 
when  the  whole  combination  of  self  and  environment 
which  makes  up  experience  seemed  likely  to  pass  under 
the  dominion  of  a  physics  much  more  iron-bound  than 
it  is  now.  That  overweening  phase,  when  it  was  almost 
necessary  to  ask  the  permission  of  physics  to  call  one's 
soul  one's  own,  is  past.  The  change  gives  rise  to 
thoughts  which  ought  to  be  developed.  Even  if  we 
cannot  attain  to  much  clarity  of  constructive  thought 
we  can  discern  that  certain  assumptions,  expectations 
or  fears  are  no  longer  applicable. 

Is  it  merely  a  well-meaning  kind  of  nonsense  for  a 
physicist  to  affirm  this  necessity  for  an  outlook  beyond 
physics?  It  is  worse  nonsense  to  deny  it.  Or  as  that 
ardent  relativist  the  Red  Queen  puts  it,  "You  call  that 
nonsense,  but  I've  heard  nonsense  compared  with  which 
that  would  be  as  sensible  as  a  dictionary". 

For  if  those  who  hold  that  there  must  be  a  physical 
basis  for  everything  hold  that  these  mystical  views  are 
nonsense,  we  may  ask — What  then  is  the  physical  basis 
of  nonsense?  The  "problem  of  nonsense"  touches  the 
scientist  more  nearly  than  any  other  moral  problem. 
He  may  regard  the  distinction  of  good  and  evil  as  too 
remote  to  bother  about;  but  the  distinction  of  sense 
and  nonsense,   of  valid  and  invalid  reasoning,   must  be 


CONCLUSION  345 

accepted  at  the  beginning  of  every  scientific  inquiry. 
Therefore  it  may  well  be  chosen  for  examination  as  a 
test  case. 

If  the  brain  contains  a  physical  basis  for  the  nonsense 
which  it  thinks,  this  must  be  some  kind  of  configuration 
of  the  entities  of  physics — not  precisely  a  chemical 
secretion,  but  not  essentially  different  from  that  kind 
of  product.  It  is  as  though  when  my  brain  says  7  times 
8  are  56  its  machinery  is  manufacturing  sugar,  but 
when  it  says  7  times  8  are  6$  the  machinery  has  gone 
wrong  and  produced  chalk.  But  who  says  the  machinery 
has  gone  wrong?  As  a  physical  machine  the  brain  has 
acted  according  to  the  unbreakable  laws  of  physics; 
so  why  stigmatise  its  action?  This  discrimination  of 
chemical  products  as  good  or  evil  has  no  parallel  in 
chemistry.  We  cannot  assimilate  laws  of  thought  to 
natural  laws;  they  are  laws  which  ought  to  be  obeyed, 
not  laws  which  must  be  obeyed;  and  the  physicist  must 
accept  laws  of  thought  before  he  accepts  natural  law. 
"Ought"  takes  us  outside  chemistry  and  physics.  It 
concerns  something  which  wants  or  esteems  sugar,  not 
chalk,  sense,  not  nonsense.  A  physical  machine  cannot 
esteem  or  want  anything;  whatever  is  fed  into  it  it  will 
chaw  up  according  to  the  laws  of  its  physical  machinery. 
That  which  in  the  physical  world  shadows  the  nonsense 
in  the  mind  affords  no  ground  for  its  condemnation.  In  a 
world  of  aether  and  electrons  we  might  perhaps  encounter 
nonsense;  we  could  not  encounter  damned  nonsense. 

The  most  plausible  physical  theory  of  correct  rea- 
soning would  probably  run  somewhat  as  follows.  By 
reasoning  we  are  sometimes  able  to  predict  events 
afterwards  confirmed  by  observation;  the  mental  pro- 
cesses follow  a  sequence  ending  in  a  conception  which 
anticipates  a  subsequent  perception.     We  may  call  such 


346  CONCLUSION 

a  chain  of  mental  states  "successful  reasoning" — 
intended  as  a  technical  classification  without  any  moral 
implications  involving  the  awkward  word  "ought".  We 
can  examine  what  are  the  common  characteristics  of 
various  pieces  of  successful  reasoning.  If  we  apply  this 
analysis  to  the  mental  aspects  of  the  reasoning  we  obtain 
laws  of  logic;  but  presumably  the  analysis  could  also 
be  applied  to  the  physical  constituents  of  the  brain.  It 
is  not  unlikely  that  a  distinctive  characteristic  would  be 
found  in  the  physical  processes  in  the  brain-cells  which 
accompany  successful  reasoning,  and  this  would  con- 
stitute "the  physical  basis  of  success." 

But  we  do  not  use  reasoning  power  solely  to  predict 
observational  events,  and  the  question  of  success  (as 
above  defined)  does  not  always  arise.  Nevertheless  if 
such  reasoning  were  accompanied  by  the  product  which 
I  have  called  "the  physical  basis  of  success"  we  should 
naturally  assimilate  it  to  successful  reasoning. 

And  so  if  I  persuade  my  materialist  opponent  to 
withdraw  the  epithet  "damned  nonsense"  as  inconsistent 
with  his  own  principles  he  is  still  entitled  to  allege  that 
my  brain  in  evolving  these  ideas  did  not  contain  the 
physical  basis  of  success.  As  there  is  some  danger  of 
our  respective  points  of  view  becoming  mixed  up,  I 
must  make  clear  my  contention: 

(a)  If  I  thought  like  my  opponent  I  should  not  worry 
about  the  alleged  absence  of  a  physical  basis  of  success 
in  my  reasoning,  since  it  is  not  obvious  why  this  should 
be  demanded  when  we  are  not  dealing  with  observa- 
tional predictions. 

(b)  As  I  do  not  think  like  him,  I  am  deeply  perturbed 
by  the  allegation;  because  I  should  consider  it  to  be  the 
outward  sign  that  the  stronger  epithet  (which  is  not 
inconsistent  with  my  principles)  is  applicable. 


CONCLUSION  347 

I  think  that  the  "success"  theory  of  reasoning  will 
not  be  much  appreciated  by  the  pure  mathematician. 
For  him  reasoning  is  a  heaven-sent  faculty  to  be  enjoyed 
remote  from  the  fuss  of  external  Nature.  It  is  heresy 
to  suggest  that  the  status  of  his  demonstrations  depends 
on  the  fact  that  a  physicist  now  and  then  succeeds  in 
predicting  results  which  accord  with  observation.  Let 
the  external  world  behave  as  irrationally  as  it  will,  there 
will  remain  undisturbed  a  corner  of  knowledge  where 
he  may  happily  hunt  for  the  roots  of  the  Riemann- 
Zeta  function.  The  "success"  theory  naturally  justifies 
itself  to  the  physicist.  He  employs  this  type  of  activity 
of  the  brain  because  it  leads  him  to  what  he  wants — a 
verifiable  prediction  as  to  the  external  world — and  for 
that  reason  he  esteems  it.  Why  should  not  the  theo- 
logian employ  and  esteem  one  of  the  mental  processes 
of  unreason  which  leads  to  what  he  wants — an  assurance 
of  future  bliss,  or  a  Hell  to  frighten  us  into  better 
behaviour?  Understand  that  I  do  not  encourage  theo- 
logians to  despise  reason;  my  point  is  that  they  might 
well  do  so  if  it  had  no  better  justification  than  the 
"success"  theory. 

And  so  my  own  concern  lest  I  should  have  been 
talking  nonsense  ends  in  persuading  me  that  I  have  to 
reckon  with  something  that  could  not  possibly  be 
found  in  the  physical  world. 

Another  charge  launched  against  these  lectures  may 
be  that  of  admitting  some  degree  of  supernaturalism, 
which  in  the  eyes  of  many  is  the  same  thing  as  super- 
stition. In  so  far  as  supernaturalism  is  associated  with 
the  denial  of  strict  causality  (p.  309)  I  can  only  answer 
that  that  is  what  the  modern  scientific  development  of 
the  quantum  theory  brings  us  to.  But  probably  the 
more  provocative  part  of  our  scheme  is  the  role  allowed 


348  CONCLUSION 

to  mind   and   consciousness.      Yet   I   suppose   that   our 
adversary  admits  consciousness  as  a  fact  and  he  is  aware 
that    but    for    knowledge     by    consciousness     scientific 
investigation    could   not   begin.      Does    he    regard   con- 
sciousness   as   supernatural?      Then    it    is    he    who    is 
admitting  the  supernatural.     Or  does  he   regard  it  as 
part  of  Nature?    So  do  we.     We  treat  it  in  what  seems 
to  be  its  obvious  position  as  the  avenue  of  approach  to 
the   reality  and  significance   of  the  world,   as  it  is  the 
avenue  of  approach  to  all  scientific  knowledge  of  the 
world.     Or  does  he  regard  consciousness  as  something 
which  unfortunately  has  to  be  admitted  but  which  it  is 
scarcely  polite  to  mention?     Even  so  we  humour  him. 
We    have    associated    consciousness   with   a    background 
untouched  in  the  physical  survey  of  the  world  and  have 
given  the  physicist  a  domain  where  he  can  go  round  in 
cycles    without   ever    encountering   anything    to    bring    a 
blush  to  his  cheek.      Here   a   realm   of   natural  law  is 
secured  to  him  covering  all  that  he  has  ever  effectively 
occupied.     And  indeed   it  has  been   quite   as  much  the 
purpose  of  our  discussion  to  secure  such  a  realm  where 
scientific  method  may  work  unhindered,  as  to  deal  with 
the   nature    of   that  part   of  our   experience   which   lies 
beyond  it.     This  defence  of  scientific  method  may  not 
be  superfluous.     The  accusation  is  often  made  that,  by 
its  neglect  of  aspects  of  human  experience   evident  to 
a    wider   culture,    physical    science    has    been    overtaken 
by   a  kind  of  madness   leading  it  sadly   astray.      It   is 
part   of  our  contention   that   there   exists   a   wide   field 
of   research    for  which  the   methods   of  physics   suffice, 
into  which  the  introduction  of  these  other  aspects  would 
be  entirely  mischievous. 

A  besetting  temptation  of  the  scientific  apologist  for 
religion  is  to  take  some  of  its  current  expressions  and 


CONCLUSION  349 

after  clearing  away  crudities  of  thought  (which  must 
necessarily  be  associated  with  anything  adapted  to  the 
everyday  needs  of  humanity)  to  water  down  the  meaning 
until  little  is  left  that  could  possibly  be  in  opposition 
to  science  or  to  anything  else.  If  the  revised  interpre- 
tation had  first  been  presented  no  one  would  have  raised 
vigorous  criticism;  on  the  other  hand  no  one  would  have 
been  stirred  to  any  great  spiritual  enthusiasm.  It  is  the 
less  easy  to  steer  clear  of  this  temptation  because  it  is 
necessarily  a  question  of  degree.  Clearly  if  we  are  to 
extract  from  the  tenets  of  a  hundred  different  sects  any 
coherent  view  to  be  defended  some  at  least  of  them  must 
be  submitted  to  a  watering-down  process.  I  do  not 
know  if  the  reader  will  acquit  me  of  having  succumbed 
to  this  temptation  in  the  passages  where  I  have  touched 
upon  religion;  but  I  have  tried  to  make  a  fight  against  it. 
Any  apparent  failure  has  probably  arisen  in  the  following 
way.  We  have  been  concerned  with  the  borderland  of 
the  material  and  spiritual  worlds  as  approached  from  the 
side  of  the  former.  From  this  side  all  that  we  could 
assert  of  the  spiritual  world  would  be  insufficient  to 
justify  even  the  palest  brand  of  theology  that  is  not  too 
emaciated  to  have  any  practical  influence  on  man's 
outlook.  But  the  spiritual  world  as  understood  in  any 
serious  religion  is  by  no  means  a  colourless  domain. 
Thus  by  calling  this  hinterland  of  science  a  spiritual 
world  I  may  seem  to  have  begged  a  vital  question, 
whereas  I  intended  only  a  provisional  identification.  To 
make  it  more  than  provisional  an  approach  must  be  made 
from  the  other  side.  I  am  unwilling  to  play  the  amateur 
theologian,  and  examine  this  approach  in  detail.  I  have, 
however,  pointed  out  that  the  attribution  of  religious 
colour  to  the  domain  must  rest  on  inner  conviction;  and 
I   think  we   should  not   deny   validity   to    certain   inner 


35o  CONCLUSION 

convictions,  which  seem  parallel  with  the  unreasoning 
trust  in  reason  which  is  at  the  basis  of  mathematics,  with 
an  innate  sense  of  the  fitness  of  things  which  is  at  the 
basis  of  the  science  of  the  physical  world,  and  with  an 
irresistible  sense  of  incongruity  which  is  at  the  basis  of 
the  justification  of  humour.  Or  perhaps  it  is  not  so  much 
a  question  of  asserting  the  validity  of  these  convictions 
as  of  recognising  their  function  as  an  essential  part  of 
our  nature.  We  do  not  defend  the  validity  of  seeing 
beauty  in  a  natural  landscape;  we  accept  with  gratitude 
the  fact  that  we  are  so  endowed  as  to  see  it  that  way. 

It  will  perhaps  be  said  that  the  conclusion  to  be 
drawn  from  these  arguments  from  modern  science,  is 
that  religion  first  became  possible  for  a  reasonable 
scientific  man  about  the  year  1927.  If  we  must  consider 
that  tiresome  person,  the  consistently  reasonable  man, 
we  may  point  out  that  not  merely  religion  but  most  of 
the  ordinary  aspects  of  life  first  became  possible  for  him 
in  that  year.  Certain  common  activities  (e.g.  falling  in 
love)  are,  I  fancy,  still  forbidden  him.  If  our  expectation 
should  prove  well  founded  that  1927  has  seen  the  final 
overthrow  of  strict  causality  by  Heisenberg,  Bohr,  Born 
and  others,  the  year  will  certainly  rank  as  one  of  the 
greatest  epochs  in  the  development  of  scientific  philo- 
sophy. But  seeing  that  before  this  enlightened  era  men 
managed  to  persuade  themselves  that  they  had  to  mould 
their  own  material  future  notwithstanding  the  yoke  of 
strict  causality,  they  might  well  use  the  same  modus 
vivendi  in  religion. 

This  brings  us  to  consider  the  view  often  pontifically 
asserted  that  there  can  be  no  conflict  between  science 
and  religion  because  they  belong  to  altogether  different 
realms  of  thought.  The  implication  is  that  discussions 
such  as  we  have  been  pursuing  are  superfluous.     But  it 


CONCLUSION  351 

seems  to  me  rather  that  the  assertion  challenges  this  kind 
of  discussion — to  see  how  both  realms  of  thought  can 
be  associated  independently  with  our  existence.  Having 
seen  something  of  the  way  in  which  the  scientific  realm 
of  thought  has  constituted  itself  out  of  a  self-closed 
cyclic  scheme  we  are  able  to  give  a  guarded  assent.  The 
conflict  will  not  be  averted  unless  both  sides  confine 
themselves  to  their  proper  domain;  and  a  discussion 
which  enables  us  to  reach  a  better  understanding  as  to 
the  boundary  should  be  a  contribution  towards  a  state 
of  peace.  There  is  still  plenty  of  opportunity  for  frontier 
difficulties;  a  particular  illustration  will  show  this. 

A  belief  not  by  any  means  confined  to  the  more 
dogmatic  adherents  of  religion  is  that  there  is  a  future 
non-material  existence  in  store  for  us.  Heaven  is  no- 
where in  space,  but  it  is  in  time.  (All  the  meaning  of 
the  belief  is  bound  up  with  the  word  future;  there  is  no 
comfort  in  an  assurance  of  bliss  in  some  former  state  of 
existence.)  On  the  other  hand  the  scientist  declares  that 
time  and  space  are  a  single  continuum,  and  the  modern 
idea  of  a  Heaven  in  time  but  not  in  space  is  in  this 
respect  more  at  variance  with  science  than  the  pre- 
Copernican  idea  of  a  Heaven  above  our  heads.  The 
question  I  am  now  putting  is  not  whether  the  theologian 
or  the  scientist  is  right,  but  which  is  trespassing  on  the 
domain  of  the  other?  Cannot  theology  dispose  of  the 
destinies  of  the  human  soul  in  a  non-material  way 
without  trespassing  on  the  realm  of  science?  Cannot 
science  assert  its  conclusions  as  to  the  geometry  of  the 
space-time  continuum  without  trespassing  on  the  realm 
of  theology?  According  to  the  assertion  above  science 
and  theology  can  make  what  mistakes  they  please 
provided  that  they  make  them  in  their  own  territory ;  they 
cannot  quarrel  if  they  keep  to  their  own  realms.     But 


352  CONCLUSION 

it  will   require  a  skilful  drawing  of  the   boundary  line 
to  frustrate  the  development  of  a  conflict  here.* 

The  philosophic  trend  of  modern  scientific  thought 
differs  markedly  from  the  views  of  thirty  years  ago. 
Can  we  guarantee  that  the  next  thirty  years  will  not  see 
another  revolution,  perhaps  even  a  complete  reaction? 
We  may  certainly  expect  great  changes,  and  by  that 
time  many  things  will  appear  in  a  new  aspect.  That  is 
one  of  the  difficulties  in  the  relations  of  science  and 
philosophy;  that  is  why  the  scientist  as  a  rule  pays  so 
little  heed  to  the  philosophical  implications  of  his  own 
discoveries.  By  dogged  endeavour  he  is  slowly  and 
tortuously  advancing  to  purer  and  purer  truth;  but  his 
ideas  seem  to  zigzag  in  a  manner  most  disconcerting 
to  the  onlooker.  Scientific  discovery  is  like  the  fitting 
together  of  the  pieces  of  a  great  jig-saw  puzzle;  a 
revolution  of  science  does  not  mean  that  the  pieces 
already  arranged  and  interlocked  have  to  be  dispersed; 
it  means  that  in  fitting  on  fresh  pieces  we  have  had  to 
revise  our  impression  of  what  the  puzzle-picture  is 
going  to  be  like.  One  day  you  ask  the  scientist  how  he  is 
getting  on;  he  replies,  "Finely.  I  have  very  nearly 
finished  this  piece  of  blue  sky."  Another  day  you  ask 
how  the  sky  is  progressing  and  are  told,  "I  have  added  a 
lot  more,  but  it  was  sea,  not  sky;  there's  a  boat  floating  on 
the  top  of  it".  Perhaps  next  time  it  will  have  turned  out 
to  be  a  parasol  upside  down ;  but  our  friend  is  still  enthusi- 
astically delighted  with  the  progress  he  is  making.  The 
scientist  has  his  guesses  as  to  how  the  finished  picture  will 
work  out;  he  depends  largely  on  these  in  his  search  for 
other  pieces  to  fit;  but  his  guesses  are  modified  from  time 
to  time  by  unexpected  developments  as  the  fitting  pro- 

*This   difficulty   is   evidently   connected    with    the    dual    entry   of   time 
into  our  experience  to  which  I  have  so  often  referred. 


CONCLUSION  353 

ceeds.  These  revolutions  of  thought  as  to  the  final 
picture  do  not  cause  the  scientist  to  lose  faith  in  his 
handiwork,  for  he  is  aware  that  the  completed  portion 
is  growing  steadily.  Those  who  look  over  his  shoulder 
and  use  the  present  partially  developed  picture  for 
purposes  outside  science,  do  so  at  their  own  risk. 

The  lack  of  finality  of  scientific  theories  would  be  a 
very  serious  limitation  of  our  argument,  if  we  had  staked 
much  on  their  permanence.  The  religious  reader  may 
well  be  content  that  I  have  not  offered  him  a  God 
revealed  by  the  quantum  theory,  and  therefore  liable 
to  be  swept  away  in  the  next  scientific  revolution.  It  is 
not  so  much  the  particular  form  that  scientific  theories 
have  now  taken — the  conclusions  which  we  believe  we 
have  proved — as  the  movement  of  thought  behind  them 
that  concerns  the  philosopher.  Our  eyes  once  opened, 
we  may  pass  on  to  a  yet  newer  outlook  on  the  world, 
but  we  can  never  go  back  to  the  old  outlook. 

If  the  scheme  of  philosophy  which  we  now  rear  on 
the  scientific  advances  of  Einstein,  Bohr,  Rutherford 
and  others  is  doomed  to  fall  in  the  next  thirty  years,  it 
is  not  to  be  laid  to  their  charge  that  we  have  gone  astray. 
Like  the  systems  of  Euclid,  of  Ptolemy,  of  Newton, 
which  have  served  their  turn,  so  the  systems  of  Einstein 
and  Heisenberg  may  give  way  to  some  fuller  realisation 
of  the  world.  But  in  each  revolution  of  scientific  thought 
new  words  are  set  to  the  old  music,  and  that  which  has 
gone  before  is  not  destroyed  T^ut  refocussed.  Amid  all 
our  faulty  attempts  at  expression  the  kernel  of  scientific 
truth  steadily  grows;  and  of  this  truth  it  may  be  said — 
The  more  it  changes,  the  more  it  remains  the  same 
thing. 


INDEX 


A  B  C  of  physics,  xiv,  88 

A  priori  probability,  77,  244,  305 

Absolute,   23,   56;   past  and  future, 

48,  57,  295;  elsewhere,  49,  50; 

values,  288,  331;  future  perfect, 

307 
Absorption  of  light,  184,  186 
Abstractions,  53 

Accelerated  frames  of  reference,  113 
Acceleration,  relativity  of,  129 
Action,  180,  241;  atom  of,  182 
Actuality,  266,  319 
Aether,  nature  of,  31 
Aether-drag,  3 
Age  of  the  sun,  169 
And,  study  of,  104 
Anthropomorphic      conception      of 

deity,  282,  337,  341 
Antisymmetrical        properties        of 

world,  236 
Ape-like  ancestors,  16,  81,  273 
Apple   (Newton's),  hi,  115 
Arrow,  Time's,  69,  79,  88,  295 
Astronomer  Royal's  time,  36,  40 
Atom,  structure  of,  1,  190,  199,  224 
Atom  of  action,  182.     See  Quantum 
Atomicity,  laws  of,  236,  245 
Averages,  300 
Awareness,  16,  334 

Background    of    pointer    readings, 

137,  255,  259,  268,  330,  339 
Balance  sheet,  33 
Beats,  216 

Beauty,  105,  267,  350 
Becoming,  68,  87 
Beginning  of  time,  83 
Berkeley,  Bishop,  xii,  326 


Beta  (3)  particle,  59 

Bifurcation  of  the  world,  236 

Billiard  ball  atoms,  2,  259 

Blessed  gods  (Hegel),  147,  155 

Bohr,  N.,  2,  185,  191,  196,  220,  306 

Boltzmann,  L.,  63 

Bombardment,  molecular,  113,  131 

Born,  M.,  208 

Bose,  S.  N.,  203 

Bragg,  W.  H.,  194 

Brain,  260,  268,  279,  311,  323 

Broad,  C.  D.,  160 

de  Broglie,  L.,  201,  202 

Building  material,  230 

Bursar,  237 

Casual  and  essential  characteristics, 

142 
Categories,  xi,  105 
Causality,  297 
Cause  and  effect,  295 
Cepheid  variables,  165 
Chalk,  calculation  of  motion  of,  107 
Chance,  72,  77,  189 
Classical  laws  and  quantum  laws, 

193,  195,  308 
Classical  physics,  4 
Clifford,  W.  K.,  278 
Clock,  99,  134,  154 
Code-numbers,  55,  81,  235,  277 
Coincidences,  71 
Collection-box  theory,  187,  193 
Colour    and    wave-length,    88,    94, 

329,  34i 
Commonsense  knowledge,  16 

Companion  of  Sirius,  203 

Comparability  of  relations,  232 

Compensation  of  errors,  12 


355 


356 


INDEX 


Concrete,  273 

Configuration  space,  219 

Conservation,  laws  of,  236,  241 

Constellations,  subjectivity  of,  95, 
106,  241 

Contiguous  relations,  233 

Contraction,  FitzGerald,  5,  24; 
reality  of,  32,  53 

Controlling  laws,  151,  245 

Conversion,  336 

Conviction,  333,  350 

Co-ordinates,  208,  231 

Copenhagen  school,  195 

Correspondence  principle,  196 

Counts  of  stars,  163 

Crudeness  of  scale  and  clock  sur- 
vey, 154 

Curvature  of  space-time,  119,  127, 
157;  coefficients  of,  120,  155 

Cyclic  method  of  physics,  260,  277, 

Cylindrical  curvature,  139 

Darwin,  G.  H.,  171 

Deflection  of  light  by  gravity,  122 

Demon  (gravitation),  118,  309 

Dense  matter,  203 

Design,  77 

Detailed  balancing,  principle  of,  80 

Determinism,  228,  271,  294,  303,  310 

Differential  equations,  282,  329,  341 

Diffraction  of  electrons,  202 

Dimension,  fourth,  52;  beyond 
fourth,  120,  158,  219 

Dirac,  P.  A.  M.,  208,  219,  270 

Directed  radius,  140 

Direction,  relativity  of,  26 

Distance,  relativity  of,  25;  inscru- 
table nature  of,  81;  macroscop- 
ic character,  155,  201 

Door,  scientific  ingress  through,  342 

Doppler  effect,  45,  184 

Double  stars,  175 

Dual  recognition  of  time,  51,  91,  99, 
334,  352 


Duration  and  becoming,  79,  99 
Dynamic  quality  of  time,  68,  90,  92, 
260 

Eclipses,  prediction  of,  149,  299 

Ego,  97,  282,  315 

Egocentric  attitude  of  observer,  15, 
61,  112 

Einstein,  A.,  1,  53,  in,  185,  203 

Einstein's  law  of  gravitation,  120, 
J39»  I5I>  260;  law  of  motion, 
124 

Einstein's  theory,  20,  111 

Electrical  theory  of  matter,  2,  6 

Electromagnetism,  236 

Electron,  3 ;  mass  of,  59 ;  extension 
in  time,  146;  in  the  atom,  188, 
199,  224;  nature  of,  279,  290 

Elephant,  problem  of,  251 

Elliptical  space,  289 

Elsewhere,  42 

Emission  of  light,  183,  191,  216 

Encounters  of  stars,  177 

Engineer,  superseded  by  mathe- 
matician, 104,  209 

Entropy,  74,   105 

Entropy-change  and  Becoming,  88 

Entropy-clock,  101 

Environment,  288,  328 

Epistemology,  225,  304 

Erg-seconds,  179 

Essential  characteristics,  142 

Euclidean  geometry,  159 

Events,  location  of,  41 ;  point- 
events,  49 

Evolution,  irreversibility  of,  91 ;  in 
stellar  system,  167,  176 

Exact  science,  250 

Existence,  286 

Experience,  288,  328 

Explanation,  scientific  ideal  of,  xiii, 
138,  209,  248 

Extensive  abstraction,  method  of, 
249 

External  world,  284 


INDEX 


357 


Familiar  and  scientific  worlds,  xiii, 
247,  324 

Fictitious  lengths,  19 

Field,  153 

Field-physics,  236 

Finite  but  unbounded  space,  80,  139, 
166,  289 

FitzGerald  contraction,  5,  24;  real- 
ity of,  32,  53 

Flat  world,  118,  138 

Flatness  of  galaxy,  164 

Force,  124 

Formality  of  taking  place,  68 

Fortuitous  concourse  of  atoms,  77, 
251 

Fourth  dimension,  52,  231 

Fowler,  R.  H.,  204 

Frames  of  space  and  time,  14,  20, 
35,  61,  112,  155 

Freak  (solar  system),  176 

Freewill,  295 

Fullness  of  space,  measures  of,  153 

Future,  relative  and  absolute,  48 ; 
see  Predictability 

Future  life,  351 

Future  perfect  tense,  307 

Galactic  system,  163 

Geloeology,  335 

General  theory  of  relativity,  in, 
129 

Generation  of  Waves  by  Wind, 
316 

Geodesic,  125 

Geometrisation  of  physics,  136 

Geometry,  133,  157,  161 

Grain  of  the  world,  48,  55,  56,  90 

Gravitation,  relative  and  absolute 
features,  114;  as  curvature, 
118;  law  of,  120,  139;  explana- 
tion of,  138,  145 

Greenland,  117 

Gross  appliances,  survey  with,  154 

Growth,  idea  of,  87 

Group  velocity,  213 


h,  179,  183,  223 

Halo  of  reality,  282,  285,  290 

Hamilton,  W.  R.,  181 

Hamiltonian  differentiation,  240 

Heaven,  351 

Hegel,  147 

Heisenberg,  W.,  206,  220,  228,  306 

Heredity,  250 

Here-Now,  41 

Heterodyning,  216 

Hour-glass  figures,  48 

House  that  Jack  Built,  262 

Hubble,  E.  P.,  167 

Humour,  322,  335 

Humpty  Dumpty,  64 

Huxley,  T.  H.,  173 

Hydrodynamics,  242,  316 

Hydrogen,  3 

Hyperbolic  geometry,  136 

Hypersphere,  81,  157 

i    (square  root  of  —  1),   135,   146, 

208 
Identical  laws,  237 
Identity  replacing  causation,  156 
Illusion,  320 

Impossibility  and  improbability,  75 
Impressionist  scheme  of  physics,  103 
Indeterminacy,    principle    of,    220, 

306 
Inertia,  124 

Inference,  chain  of,  270,  298 
Infinity,  80 

Infra-red  photography,  173 
Inner  Light,  327 

Insight,  89,  91,  268,  277,  311,  339 
Instants,  world-wide,  43 
Integers,  220,  246 
Interval,  37,  261 
Intimate   and    symbolic  knowledge, 

321 
Introspection,  321 
Invariants,  23 
Inventory    method,    103,    106,    280, 

341 


358 


INDEX 


Inverse-square  law,  29 

Island  universes,  165 

Isotropic  directed  curvature,  144 

Jabberwocky,  291 
Jeans,  J.  H.,  176,  187 
Johnson,  Dr.,  326 
Jordan,  P.,  208 

Knowable  to  mind,  264 
Knowledge,  nature  of  physical,  257, 
304;  complete,  226 

Laplace,  176 

Laputans,  341 

Larmor,  J.,  7 

Laws  of  Nature,  237,  244 

Laws  of  thought,  345 

Lenard,  P.,  130 

Length,  6,  160.     See  Distance 

Life  on  other  planets,  170 

Life-insurance,  300 

Lift,  man  in  the,  111 

Light,  velocity  of,  46,  54;  emission 

of,  183,  191,  216 
Likeness  between  relations,  232 
Limitations  of  physical  knowledge, 

257 
Linkage   of   scientific   and   familiar 

worlds,  xiii,  88,  156,  239,  249 
Location,  frames  of,  14,  41 
Logos,  338 
Longest    track,    law    of,    125,    135, 

148 
Lorentz,  H.  A.,  7 
Lowell,  P.,  174 
Luck,  rays  of,  190 
Lumber    (in  world   building),   235, 

243 

Macroscopic  survey,   154,  227,  299, 

304 
Man,  169,  178 
Man-years,  180 
Mars,  172 


Mass,  increase  with  velocity,  39,  50, 

59 

Mathematician,  161,  209,  337,  347 

Matrix,  208 

Matter,  1,  31,  156,  203,  248,  262 

Maxwell,  J.  C,  8,  60,  156,  237 

Measures  of  structure,  234,  268 

Mechanical  models,  209 

Mechanics  and  Geometry,  137 

Mendelian  theory,  250 

Mental  state,  279 

Metric,  142,  153 

Metrical  and  non-metrical  proper- 
ties, 275 

Michelson-Morley  experiment,  5,  zi 

Microscopic  analysis,  reaction  from, 
103 

Milky  Way,  Z63 

Miller,  D.  C,  5 

Mind  and  matter,  259,  268,  278; 
selection  by  mind,  239,  243,  264 

Mind-stuff,  276 

Minkowski,  H.,  34,  53 

Mirror,  distortion  by  moving,  it 

Models,  198,  209,  344 

Molecular  bombardment,  113,  Z3Z 

Momentum,  153,  208,  223,  239,  262 

Monomarks,  23  z 

Moon,  origin  of,  Z7Z 

Morley,  E.  W.,  5 

Motion,  law  of,  123 

Multiplicationist,  86 

Multiplicity  of  space  and  time 
frames,  20,  35,  6z 

Myself,  42,  53 

Mysticism,  defence  of,  323 ;  reli- 
gious, 338 

Nautical  Almanac,  Z50 

Nebulae,  165 

Nebular  observers,  9,  Z2 

Neptune,  49 

Neutral  stuff,  280 

Neutral  wedge,  48 

New  quantum  theory,  206 


INDEX 


359 


Newton,    in,    122,    201;    quotation 

from,  in 
Newtonian  scheme,  4,  18,  125 
Non-empty  space,  127,  153,  238 
Non-Euclidean  geometry,    157 
Nonsense,  problem  of,  344 
Now-lines,  42,  47,  49,  184 
Nucleus  of  atom,  3 

Objectivity   of   "becoming",    94;    of 

a  picture,  107 
Observer,  attributes  of,  15,  337 
Odds,  301,  303 

Official  scientific  attitude,  286,  334 
Operator,  208 
Orbit  jumps   of  electron,   191,   196, 

205,  215,  300,  312 
Organisation,  68,  70,  104 
Ought,  345 
Oxygen  and  vegetation,  174 

/»'s  and  q's,  208,  223,  327 

Pacific  Ocean,  171 

Particle,  202,  211,  218 

Past,  relative  and  absolute,  48 

Pedantry,  340,  342 

Permanence,  241 

Personal  aspect  of  spiritual  world, 

337 
Phoenix  complex,  85 

Photoelectric  effect,   187 

Photon,  190 

Physical  time,  40 

Picture  and  paint,  106 

Picture  of  gravitation,  115,  138,  157 

Plan,  Nature's,  27 

Planck,  M.,  185 

Plurality  of  worlds,  169 

Pointer  readings,  251 

Ponderomotive  force,  237 

Porosity  of  matter,  1 

Potential   (gravitational),  261 

Potential  energy,  213 

Potential  gradient,  96 

Pound  sterling,  relativity  of,  26 


Predestination,  293,  303 

Predictability  of  events,  147,  228, 
300,  307 

Primary  law,  66,  75,  98 ;  insuffi- 
ciency of,  107 

Primary  scheme  of  physics,  76,  129, 
295 

Principal  curvature,  120,  139 

Principia,  4 

Principle,  Correspondence,   196 

Principle  of  detailed  balancing,  80 

Principle  of  indeterminacy,  220,  306 

Probability,  216,  315 

Proof  and  plausibility,  337 

Proper-distance,  25 

Proper-time,  37 

Proportion,  sense  of,  341 

Proton,  3 

Psi  {\p),  216,  305 

Pure  mathematician,  161,  337,  347 

Purpose,  105 

g-numbers,  208,  270 
Quantum,  184;  size  of,  200 
Quantum  laws,  193 
Quantum  numbers,  191,  205 
Quest  of  the  absolute,  26,   122;   of 
science,  no,  287;  of  reality,  328 
Quotations  from 

Boswell,  326 

Brooke,  Rupert,  317 

Clifford,  W.  K.,  278 

Dickens,  32 

Einstein,  A.,  294 

Hegel,  147 

Huxley,  T.  H.,  173 

Kronecker,  L.,  246 

Lamb,  H.,   316 

Lewis  Carroll,  28,  291,  344 

Milton,  167 

Newton,   in 

Nursery  Rhymes,  64,  70,  262 

Omar  Khayyam,  64,  293 

O'Shaughnessy,   A.,    325 

Russell,  Bertrand,  160,  278 


360 


INDEX 


Quotations  from  (cont.) 

Shakespeare,  21,  39,  83,  292,  330 
Swift,  341 
Whitehead,  A.  N.,  145 

Radiation  pressure,  58 

Random  element,  64;  measurement 

of,  74 

Reality,  meaning  of,  282,  326 

Really  true,  34 

Rectification  of  curves,  125 

Rejuvenescence,  theories  of,  85,  169 

Relata  and  relations,  230 

Relativity  of  velocity,  10,  54,  59,  61 ; 
of  space-frames,  21 ;  of  mag- 
netic field,  22 ;  of  distance,  25 ; 
of  pound  sterling,  26;  of  Now 
(simultaneity),  46,  61;  of  ac- 
celeration, 129;  of  standard  of 
length,  143 

Religion,    194,    281,    288,    322,    324, 

326,  333,  349 
Retrospective  symbols,  307,  308 
Revolutions  of  scientific  thought,  4, 

352 
Right  frames  of  space,  18,  20 

Roemer,  O.,  43 

Rotating  masses,  break-up  of,  176 

Running  down  of  universe,  63,  84 

Russell,  B.,  160,  277,  278 

Rutherford,  E.,  2,  327 

Scale   (measuring),  12,  18,  24,  134, 

141 
Schrodinger's  theory,  199,  210,  225, 

305 
Scientific  and  familiar  worlds,  xiii, 

247,  324 
Second  law  of  thermodynamics,  74, 

86 

Secondary  law,  75,  79,  98 

Seen-now  line9,  44,  47 

Selection    by    mind,    239,    243,    264, 

330 
Self-comparison  of  space,  145 


Sense-organs,  51,  96,  266,  329 

Shadows,  world  of,  xiv,  109 

Shuffling,  63,  92,  184 

Sidereal  universe,  163 

Signals,  speed  of,  57 

Significances,   108,  329 

Simultaneity,  49,  61 

Singularities,  127 

Sirius,  Companion  of,  203 

de  Sitter,  W.,  167 

Slithy  toves,  291 

Solar  system,  origin  of,  176 

Solar  system  type  of  atom,  2,  190 

Sorting,  93 

Space,  14,   16,  51,  81,  137 

Spasmodic  moon,  226 

Spatial  relations,  50 

Spectral  lines,  205,  216;  displace- 
ment of,  121,  166 

Spherical  curvature,  radius  of, 
14c 

Spherical  space,  82,  166,  289;  ra- 
dius of,  167 

Spiral  nebulae,  165 

Spiritual  world,  281,  288,  324,   349 

Standard  metre,  141 

Stars,  number  of,  163 ;  double,  175 ; 
evolution  of,  176;  white 
dwarfs,  203 

States,  197,  301 

Statistical  laws,  244;  mind's  inter- 
ference with,  313 

Statistics,  201,  300,  303 

Stratification,  47 

Stress,  129,  155,  262 

Structure,  234,  277 

Sub-aether,  211,  219 

Subjective  element  in  physics,  95, 
241 

Substance,  ix,  273,  318 

Success,  physical  basis  of,  346 

Sun,  as  a  star,  164;  age  of,  169 

Supernatural,  309,  348 

Survey  from  within,  145,  321,  330 

Sweepstake  theory,   189 


INDEX 


361 


Symbolism  in  science,  xiii,  209,  247, 

269,  324 
Synthetic  method  of  physics,  249 

Temperature,  71 

Temporal  relations,  50 

Tensor,  257 

Tensor  calculus,  181 

Thermodynamical  equilibrium,  77 

Thermodynamics,  second  law  of, 
66,  74,  86 

Thermometer  as  entropy-clock,  99, 
101 

Thinking  machine,  259 

Thought,  258 ;  laws  of,  345 

Time  in  physics,  36;  time  lived 
(proper-time),  40;  dual  recog- 
nition of,  51,  100;  time's  arrow, 
69;  infinity  of,  83;  summary  of 
conclusions,  101 ;  time-triangies, 
133  ;  reality  of,  275 

Time-scale  in  astronomy,  167 

Touch,  sense  of,  273 

Track,  longest,  125,  135,  148 

Trade  Union  of  matter,  126 

Transcendental  laws,  245 

Traveller,  time   lived   by,   39,    126, 

135 

Triangles  in  space  and  time,  133 

Tug  of  gravitation,  115,  122 

Undoing,  65 
Unhappening,  94,  108 
Uniformity,  basis  of,  145 


Unknowable  entities,  221,  308 
Utopia,  265 

Values,  243,  330 
Vegetation  on  Mars,   173 
Velocity,    relativity    of,    10;    upper 

limit  to,  56 
Velocity  through  aether,  30,  32 
Velocity  of  light,  46,  54 
Venus,  170 
Victorian   physicist,  ideals   of,  209, 

259 
View-point,  92,  283 
Void,   13,   137 
Volition,  310 

Watertight  compartments,   194 

Wave-group,   213,  217,   225 

Wave-length,  measurement  of,  24 

Wave-mechanics,  211 

Wave-theory  of  matter,  202 

Wavicle,  201 

Wells,  H.  G.,  67 

White  dwarfs,  203 

Whitehead,  A.  N.,  145,  249 

Whittaker,  E.  T.,  181 

Winding  up  of  universe,  83 

World  building,  230 

World-lines,  253 

Worm,  four-dimensional,  42,  87,  92 

Wright,  W.  H.,  172 

Wrong  frames  of  reference,  116 

X  (Mr.),  262,  268 


{