Skip to main content

Full text of "Nietzsche : his life and works"

See other formats


^OBARTS 


to 


of 


Rev.  N.   Cacciapuoti 


M 

PHILOSOPHIES  ANCIENT  AND  MODERN 


NIETZSCHE 


RELIGIONS:   ANCIENT  AND   MODERN 

Animism.    By  EDWARD  CLODD,  author  of  The  Story  of  Creation. 
Pantheism.     By  JAMES  ALLANSON  PICTON,  author  of  The  Religion  of  the 

Universe. 
The  Religions  Of  Ancient  China.    By  Professor  GILES,  LL.  D. ,  Professor 

of  Chinese  in  the  University  of  Cambridge. 
The  Religion  Of  Ancient  Greece.     By  JANE  HARBISON,  Lecturer  at 

Newnham  College,  Cambridge,  author  of  Prolegomena  to  Study  of  Greek 

Religion. 
Islam.    By  the  Rt.  Hon.  AMEER  ALI  SYED,  of  the  Judicial  Committee  of  His 

Majesty's  Privy  Council,  author  of  The  Spirit  of  Islam  and  Ethics  of  Islam. 
Magic  and  Fetishism.      By  Dr.   A.   C.   HADDON,   F.R.S.,  Lecturer  on 

Ethnology  at  Cambridge  University. 
The  Religion  Of  Ancient  Egypt.    By  Professor  W.  M.  FLINDERS  PETRIE, 

F.R.S. 
The  Religion  of  Babylonia  and  Assyria.    By  THEOPHII.US  G.  PINCHES, 

late  of  the  British  Museum. 
Early  Buddhism.    By  Professor  RHYS  DAVIDS,  LL.D.,  late  Secretary  of 

The  Royal  Asiatic  Society. 
Hinduism.    By  Dr.  L.  D.  BARNETT,  of  the  Department  of  Oriental  Printed 

Books  and  MSS.,  British  Museum. 
Scandinavian  Religion.    By  WILLIAM  A.  CRAIOIE,  Joint  Editor  of  the 

Oxford  English  Dictionary. 
Celtic  Religion.    By  Professor  ANWYL,  Professor  of  Welsh  at  University 

College,  Aberystwyth. 

The  Mythology  of  Ancient  Britain  and  Ireland.     By  CHARLES 

SQUIRE,  author  of  The  Mythology  of  the  British  Islands. 

Judaism.     By  ISRAEL  ABRAHAMS,  Lecturer  in  Talmudic  Literature  in  Cam 
bridge  University,  author  of  Jewish  Life  in  the  Middle  Ages. 

The  Religion  of  Ancient  Rome.    By  CYRIL  BAILEY,  M.A. 

Shinto,  The  Ancient  Religion  of  Japan.    By  W.  G.  ASTON,  C.  M.  G. 

The  Religion  of  Ancient  Mexico  and  Peru.    By  LEWIS  SPENCE,  M.A. 

Early  Christianity.     By  S.  B.  BLACK,  Professor  at  M'Gill  University. 

The  Psychological  Origin  and  Nature  of  Religion.    By  Professor 

J.  H.  LEUBA. 

The  Religion  of  Ancient  Palestine.    By  STANLEY  A.  COOK. 
Mithraism.    By  W.  J.  PHYTHIAN-ADAMS. 

PHILOSOPHIES 

Early  Greek  Philosophy.    By  A.  W.  BENN,  author  of  The  Philosophy  of 

Greece,  Rationalism  in  the  Nineteenth  Century. 
Stoicism.     By  Professor  ST.  GEORGE  STOCK,  author  of  Deductive  Logic, 

editor  of  the  Apology  of  Plato,  etc. 
Plato.     By  Professor  A.  E.  TAYLOR,  St.  Andrews  University,  author  of 

The  Problem  of  Conduct. 
Scholasticism.    By  Father  RICKABY,  S.  J. 
Hobbes.    By  Professor  A.  E.  TAYLOR. 
Locke.    By  Professor  ALEXANDER,  of  Owens  College. 
Comte  and  Mill.    By  T.  WHITTAKER,  author  of  The  Neoplatonists  Apollo- 

nius  of  Tyana  and  other  Essays. 
Herbert   Spencer.     By  W.   H.  HUDSON,  author  of  An  Introduction  to 

Spencer's  Philosophy. 
Schopenhauer.    By  T.  WHITTAKER. 

Berkeley.    By  Professor  CAMPBELL  FRASER,  D.C.L.,  LL.D. 
Swedenborg.    By  Dr.  SEW  ALL. 

Nietzsche :  His  Life  and  Works.    By  ANTHONY  M.  LUDOVICI. 
Bergson,     By  JOSEPH  SOLOMON. 
Rationalism.    By  J.  M.  ROBERTSON. 
P-iagmatism.    By  D.  L.  MURRAY. 
Rudolf  Eucken.    By  W.  TUDER- JONES. 


NIETZSCHE 

His  Life  and  Works 


By 

ANTHONY    M.    LUDOVICI 

AUTHOR    OF 

4  WHO    IS    TO    BE    MASTER    OF    THE    WORLD?" 
AND    C  NOTES    TO    ZARATHUSTRA  * 


Preface  by 
DR.   OSCAR    LEVY 


LONDON 
CONSTABLE    fef    COMPANY    LTD 

10  ORANGE  STREET  LEICESTER  SQUARE 
1914 


PREFACE 

THE  commission  for  a  book  on  Nietzsche,  to  form 
the  latest  addition  to  a  series  of  famous  philoso 
phers,  is  most  certainly  a  sign  that  the  age  of 
adversity,  through  which  the  earlier  Nietzscheans 
had  to  struggle,  has  at  last  come  to  an  end.  For 
ten  consecutive  years  they  had  had  no  reply  what 
ever  to  their  propaganda,  and  their  publications, 
loud  as  some  of  them  were,  proved  as  ineffective  as 
cannon  shots  fired  into  the  eternity  of  interplane 
tary  space.  Finally,  however,  when  the  echo  was 
at  last  heard,  it  gave  back  nothing  like  the 
original  sound :  it  was  an  echo  of  groans  and 
moans,  an  echo  of  roaring  disapproval  and  hissing 
mockery.  Yet  the  years  rolled  on  and  on — and 
so  did  the  printing-presses — hissing  and  roaring 
as  much  as  ever — but  at  last,  their  thunders  grew 
tamer  and  more  subdued — the  tempest  of  their 
fury  seemed  to  die  away  in  the  distance — occa 
sionally  a  slight  mutter  was  still  to  be  heard, 


NIETZSCHE 

but  no  more  flashes  and  hisses — and  suddenly  a 
streak  of  blue  was  observed  over  the  horizon, 
followed  by  a  ray  and  smile  of  sunlight — and 
a  soft  zephyr  of  subdued  and  tentative  compli 
ments — and  when  our  Nietzsche  edition  had 
begun  to  appear  in  its  stately  volumes  we  were 
enabled  to  receive  from  our  former  enemies  on 
both  sides  of  the  Atlantic  '  respectful  congratula 
tions.' 

And  now  all  iny  brave  friends  are  radiant 
with  joy  and  optimism.  Like  the  wanderer  in 
the  fairy  tale,  while  the  storm  of  disgust  and  loud 
reproach  was  raging,  they  wrapped  themselves  all 
the  more  closely  in  their  cloaks,  and  no  impudent 
wind  could  tear  a  shred  of  garments  from  them, 
but  now  that  the  sun  of  approval  has  set  in, 
they  would  fain  get  out  of  their  armour  and 
enjoy  the  fine  weather  as  a  reward  for  past 
perils.  Has  not  the  spring  come  at  last  ?  Are 
not  the  gay  flowers  at  our  feet  meant  to  welcome 
the  victorious  warriors  ?  .  .  ,  Are  not  the  ladies 
— ladies  that  from  time  immemorial  have  loved 
the  warrior  (especially  when  he  is  successful) — 
smiling  at  us  more  gloriously  even  than  the  sun  ? 
...  Sun,  ladies,  flowers,  smiles — was  there  ever 
a  nicer  combination  ?  .  .  . 

But,  alas  !  there  is  an  unimaginative  creature 
vi 


PREFACE 

among  the  guests,  an  earnest  face  among  the 
cheerful,  a  disbeliever  among  the  faithful,  a  dark 
countenance  amid  the  bright  assembly ; — a  being 
who,  in  glaring  contrast  to  the  sun,  the  smiles,  and 
the  gaily-coloured  dresses  and  sunshades,  is  keep 
ing  a  tight  hold  upon  a  dark  umbrella — for  he 
has  an  uncontrollable  mistrust  of  English 
weather ! 

And  I  may  claim  that  I  not  only  know  the 
meteorological  conditions  of  England,  but  also 
those  of  the  whole  of  modern  Europe.  I  know 
them  so  well  that  I  have  the  greatest  doubts 
whether  Nietzsche's  influence  will  be  strong 
enough  to  withstand  the  terrible  hurricane  of 
democracy  which  in  our  age  is  sweeping  every- 
thing  before  it,  and  leaving  a  level  plain  in  its 
rear.  Nietzsche  may  have  been  ever  so  right, 
but  Truth  and  Righteousness  do  not  always  pre 
vail  in  this  world  of  ours,  indeed,  they  don't :  the 
Bible  itself,  that  otherwise  optimistic  book,  lets 
this  grand  secret  out  once  and  only  once — in  the 
story  of  Job.  The  '  happy  ending '  in  that  book 
will  deceive  no  realistic  observer:  it  was  added 
to  the  story,  as  it  is  added  to  modern  plays 
and  novels,  for  the  edification  and  comfort 
of  the  audience:  the  true  story  of  Job  was 
without  it,  as  was  the  true  story  of  many 
vii 


NIETZSCHE 

a  brave  man,  as  was  the  true  story  of  that 
great  pope,  who  on  his  deathbed  came  out  with 
the  confession :  '  Dilexi  justitiam  et  odi  iniquita- 
tem,  propterea  morior  in  exsilio,'1  a  confession 
which  went  in  the  very  teeth  of  his  own  virtue- 
rewarding  creed  with  its  happy-go-lucky  trust  in 
the  moral  order  of  the  universe. 

Nietzsche  may  have  been  right,  therefore  he 
may  be  unsuccessful.  I  myself  regard  Nietzsche's 
views  on  art,  religion,  psychology,  morality,  as 
extremely  sound ;  I  think  they  are  proved  both 
by  history  and  by  common  experience;  I  even 
suspect  that  they  could  be  confirmed  by  science, 
if  only  science  would  give  up  looking  at  the 
world  through  the  coloured  spectacles  of  demo 
cratic  prejudice  .  .  .  but  then,  it  is  so  difficult  to 
give  up  this  democratic  prejudice;  for  it  is  by  no 
means  simply  a  political  opinion.  Democracy, 
as  a  political  creed,  need  terrify  no  one;  for 
political  creeds  succeed  each  other  like  waves  of 
the  sea,  whose  thunder  is  loud  and  whose  end  is 
froth;  but jjie  driving  power  behind  democracy 
is  not  a  political  one,  it  is  religious — it  is  Christi- 
jmity,.  A  mighty  religion  still,  a  religion  which 
has  governed  the  world  for  two  thousand  years, 

1  '  I  have  loved  justice  and  I  have  hated  iniquity,  therefore 
I  die  in  exile. ' 

viii 


PREFACE 

which  has  influenced  all  philosophies,  all  litera 
tures,  all  laws,  all  customs  up  to  our  own  day,  till 
it  has  finally  filtered  into  our  hearts,  our  blood, 
our  system,  and  become  part  and  parcel  of  our 
selves  without  our  being  aware  of  it.  At  the 
present  moment  we  are  all  instinctive  Christians. 
Even  if  this  Christian  religion  has  been  severely 
wounded  by  Nietzsche's  criticism — and  I  believe 
this  to  be  the  case  —  I  beg  to  suggest  that  a 
wounded  lion  may  still  have  more  strength  than 
all  the  fussy,  political,  rationalistic,  agnostic,  non 
conformist,  Nietzschean  and  super-Nietzschean 
mice  put  together. 

It  was  all  the  braver,  therefore,  on  Nietzsche's 
part  to  assail  such  a  mighty  enemy,  and  to  attack 
him  exactly  on  the  spot  where  attack  was  most 
needed,  if  victory  were  to  be  won.  Nietzsche 
clearly  recognised  that  the  canons  of  criticism 
had  until  now  only  been  directed  against  the 
outer  works  of  that  stalwart  fortress — at  dog 
matic,  at  supernatural,  at  ecclesiastical  Christi-  ^ 
anity,  and  that  no  one  had  yet  dared  to  aim  right 
at  the  very  heart  of  the  creed — its  morality, 
which,  while  the  shamfighters  were  at  work 
outside,  was  being  enormously  strengthened  and 
consolidated  from  within.  This  morality,  how 
ever,  Nietzsche  recognised  as  intimately  con- 
ix 


NIETZSCHE 

nected  with  modern  democracy — and  behind  the 
rosebush  of  democracy  with  its  flowery  speeches 
and  its  fraternity-  and  liberty-blossoms,  Nietzsche 
clearly  saw  the  dragon  of  anarchy  and  dissolution 
lurking.  It  was  the  mortal  fear  of  annihilation 
and  ruin  which  gave  Nietzsche  the  daring  to 
fulminate  against  our  religion  with  such  imperish 
able  Dithyrambics.  He  was  the  first  to  mean 
the  phrase, ( dcrasez  I'infdme  ! '  which  in  Voltaire's 
mouth  was  only  an  epigrammatic  exclamation. 
For  Nietzsche's  great  forerunner  on  the  Continent, 
Wolfgang  Goethe,  who  was  also  just  as  well  aware 
how  it  would  all  end,  was  much  too  prudent  a 
man  to  lay  his  innermost  heart  bare  to  his 
enemies,  he — the  grand  old  hypocrite  of  Weimar 
— gauged  the  power  of  the  contrary  current 
correctly,  and  wisely  left  the  open  combat  against 
Christianity  and  democracy  to  his  great  colleague 
— to  that  man  of  tragic  wit,  to  Heinrich  Heine. 

And  there  were  others  on  the  Continent — very 
few  to  be  sure,  and  no  politician  or  man  of  science 
or  woman  among  them — others  who  saw  the  drift 
of  modern  ideas:  all  of  them  poets.  For  poets 
are  prophets:  their  sensitive  organisation  feels 
the  fall  of  the  glass  first,  while  their  pluck  and 
their  pride,  their  duty  and  their  desire  to  face 
the  storm  drive  them  into  the  very  thick  of  it. 


PREFACE 

The  German  poet  Hebbel,  the  French  novelist 
Stendhal,  were  amongst  them.  A  new  Matthew 
Arnold — the  object  of  my  wish  for  this  country — 
would  perhaps  like  to  include  another  poet,  the 
Frenchman  Alfred  de  Vigny,  in  whose  journal 
are  to  be  found  those  awe-inspiring  words  against 
democracy:  'Alas!  it  is  thou,  Democracy,  that 
art  the  desert!  it  is  thou  who  hast  shrouded 
and  bleached  everything  beneath  thy  monticles 
of  sand !  Thy  tedious  flatness  has  covered  every 
thing  and  levelled  all!  For  ever  and  ever  the 
valley  and  the  hill  supplant  each  other ;  and  only 
from  time  to  time  a  man  of  courage  is  seen: 
he  rises  like  a  sand-whirl,  makes  his  ten  paces 
towards  the  sun,  and  then  falls  like  powder  to 
the  ground.  And  then  nothing  more  is  seen 
save  the  eternal  plain  of  endless  sand.' 

Goethe  and  Hebbel,  Stendhal  and  Heinrich 
Heine,  Alfred  de  Vigny  and  Friedrich  Nietzsche, 
all  made  their  ten  steps  towards  the  sun  and  are 
now  sleeping  peacefully  beneath  the  dry  sands  of 
Christian  democracy.  Their  works  are  read,  to 
be  sure ;  but  alas !  how  few  understand  their 
meaning!  I  see  this  and  I  shudder.  And  I 
remember  another  moment  in  my  life — a  moment 
of  perturbation  too— a  moment  in  which  an  idea 
overcame  me,  which  has  been  haunting  me  ever 
xi 


NIETZSCHE 

since.  I  was  on  a  visit  to  Mrs.  Forster-Nietzsche, 
in  her  villa  high  up  amongst  the  hills  of  Weimar, 
waiting  in  the  drawing-room  for  my  hostess  to 
enter.  It  was  the  first  time  that  I  had  stood 
upon  the  holy  ground  where  Friedrich  Nietzsche 
gave  up  his  heroic  soul,  and  I  was  naturally 
impressed ;  my  eyes  wandered  reverently  around 
the  scene,  and  I  suddenly  noticed  some  hand 
writing  on  the  wall.  The  handwriting  consisted 
of  a  powerful  letter  N  which  the  ingenious 
builder  had  engraved  profusely  upon  the  oak 
panels  of  the  room.  The  N,  of  course,  reminded 
me  of  another  big  N,  connected  with  another 
big  name, — the  N  which  used  to  be  engraved 
together  with  the  imperial  crown  and  eagle  upon 
the  plate  and  regalia  of  Napoleon  Bonaparte. 
There  was  another  victim  of  democracy:  the 
man  who,  elevated  by  its  revolutionary  wave, 
tried  to  stifle  and  subdue  the  anarchical  flood, 
was  swallowed  up  as  ignominiously  as  its  other 
implacable  opponent,  the  plucky  parson's  son  of 
the  vicarage  of  Rocken. 

The  mighty  sword  in  the  beginning  and  the 
mighty  pen  at  the  end  of  the  last  century  were 
alike  impotent  against — Fate.  No  doubt,  I  saw 
in  that  moment,  as  though  lit  up  by  a  flashlight, 
the  fate  of  Europe  clearly  before  my  eyes.  A 
xii 


PREFACE 

fate — an  iron  fate.  A  fate  unavoidable  for  a 
continent  that  will  have  no  more  guides,  no 
more  great  men.  A  fate  unavoidable  for  an  age 
that  spills  its  best  blood  with  the  carelessness  of 
ignorance.  A  fate  unavoidable  for  a  people  that 
is  driven  by  its  very  religion  to  disobedience  and 
anarchy.  And  I  thought  of  my  own  race,  which 
has  seen  so  many  fates,  so  many  ages,  so  many 
empires  decline — and  there  was  I,  the  eternal 
Jew,  witnessing  another  catastrophe.  And  I 
shuddered,  and  when  my  hostess  entered  I  had 
not  yet  recovered  my  breath. 

Gruesome,  isn't  it  ?  But  what  if  it  should  not 
come  true?  'There  are  no  more  prophets  to 
day/  says  the  Talmud  scornfully.  Well,  unlike 
my  ancestor  Jonah,  who  became  melancholic 
when  his  announcement  of  the  downfall  of 
Nineveh  was  not  fulfilled,  I  beg  to  say  that  I 
on  the  contrary  shall  be  extremely  delighted  to 
have  proved  a  false  prophet.  But  I  shall  keep 
my  umbrella  all  the  same. 

OSCAR  LEVY. 

54  RUSSELL  SQUARE, 
LONDON,  W.C. 


xiii 


CONTENTS 

PAGE 

i.  NIETZSCHE'S  LIFE,       «...,! 
ii.  NIETZSCHE  THE  A  MORALIST,  .  *  *  .        19 

in.  NIETZSCHE  THE  MORALIST,    .  .  .  .        41 

iv.  NIETZSCHE  THE  EVOLUTIONIST,          .  .  .58 

v.  NIETZSCHE  THE  SOCIOLOGIST,  .  .  .  .75 

SUMMARY  AND  CONCLUSION,  ....        97 

BOOKS   USEFUL  TO   THE  STUDENT,        .  .  .101 


XV 


ABBREVIATIONS   USED    IN    REFERRING    TO 
SOME  OF  NIETZSCHE'S  WORKS 

D.  D.  =  Dawn  of  Day. 
Z.        =  Thus  Spake  Zarathustra. 
G.  E.  =  Beyond  Good  and  Evil. 
G.  M.  =  The  Genealogy  of  Morals, 
Aph.   =  Aphorism, 


NIETZSCHE 
CHAPTER   I 

LIFE   AND   WORKS 

'  HOLY  be  thy  name  to  all  coming  generations ! 
In  the  name  of  all  thy  friends,  I,  thy  pupil,  cry 
out  our  warmest  thanks  to  thee  for  thy  great 
life. 

'  Thou  wast  one  of  the  noblest  and  purest  men 
that  ever  trod  this  earth. 

'And  although  this  is  known  to  both  friend 
and  foe,  I  do  not  deem  it  superfluous  to  utter 
this  testimony  aloud  at  thy  tomb.  For  we 
know  the  world ;  we  know  the  fate  of  Spinoza ! 
Around  Nietzsche's  memory,  too,  posterity  may 
cast  shadows !  And  therefore  I  close  with  the 
words :  Peace  to  thy  ashes  ! ' * 

This  view,  expressed  by  Peter  Gast,  Nietzsche's 
staunchest  friend  and  disciple,  at  his  master's 
graveside,  in  August  1900,  may  be  regarded 

1  Das  Leben  Friedrich  Nietzsche's  by  Frau  Forster-Nietzsche. 
A  I 


NIETZSCHE 

as  typical  of  the  Nietzsche  enthusiast's  atti 
tude  towards  his  master.  On  the  other  hand 
we  have  the  assurance  of  Nietzsche's  opponents 
and  enemies  that  nothing  could  have  been  more 
utterly  disastrous  to  modern  society,  more  per 
nicious,  dangerous,  and  ridiculous  than  Nietzsche's 
_  life-work. 

At  the  present  day  Nietzsche  is  so  potent  a 
force  and  his  influence  is  increasing  with  such 
rapidity  that,  whatever  our  calling  in  life  may 
be,  it  behoves  us  to  know  precisely  what  he 
stands  for,  and  to  which  of  the  opinions  above 
given  we  should  subscribe.  As  a  matter  of  fact, 
the  inquirer  into  the  life  and  works  of  this  in 
teresting  man  will  find  that  he  has  well-nigh  as 
many  by-naines  as  he  has  readers,  and  not  the 
least  of  our  difficulties  in  speaking  about  him  will 
be  to  give  him  a  fitting  title,  descriptive  of  his 
mission  and  the  way  in  which  he  understood  it. 

Some  deny  his  right  to  the  title  '  philosopher ' ; 
others  declare  him  to  be  a  mere  anarchist ;  and  a 
large  number  regard  all  his  later  works  as  no 
more  than  a  shallow  though  brilliant  reversal  of 
every  accepted  doctrine  on  earth. 

In  order  to  be  able  to  provoke  so  much  diversity 
of  opinion,  a  man  must  be  not  only  versatile  but 
forcible.  Nietzsche  was  both.  There  is  scarcely 

2 


LIFE  AND  WORKS 

a  subject  in  the  whole  range  of  philosophical 
thought  which  he  does  not  attack  and  blow  up ; 
and  he  hurls  forth  his  hard,  polished  missiles  in  a 
manner  so  destructive,  and  at  the  same  time  with 
such  accuracy  of  aim,  that  it  is  no  wonder  a 
chorus  of  ill-used  strongholds  of  traditional 
thought  now  cry  out  against  him  as  a  disturber 
and  annihilator  of  their  peace.  Yet,  through  all 
the  dust,  smoke,  and  noise  of  his  implacable  war 
fare,  there  are  both  a  method  and  a  mission  to  be 
discerned — a  method  and  a  mission  in  the  pursuit 
of  which  Nietzsche  is  really  as  unswerving  as  he 
seems  capricious. 

Throughout  his  life  and  all  his  many  recanta-' 
tions  and  revulsions  of  feeling,  he  remained 
faithful  to  one  purpose  and  to  one,  jiiin — the 
elevation  of  j  the  type  man.  However  bewildered 
we  may  become  beneath  the  hail  of  his  epigrams, 
treating  of  every  momentous  question  that  has 
ever  agitated  the  human  mind,  we  still  can 
trace  this  broad  principle  running  through  all 
his  works:  his  desire  to  elevate  man  and  to 
make  him  more  worthy  of  humanity's  great  past. 

Even  in  his  attack  on  English  psychologists, 
naturalists,  and  philosophers,  in  The  Genealogy  of 
Morals,  what  are  his  charges  against  them  ?  He 
says  they  debase  man,  voluntarily  or  involuntarily, 

3 


NIETZSCHE 

by  seeking  the  really  operative,  really  imperative 
and  decisive  factor  in  history  precisely  where  the 
intellectual  pride  of  man  would  least  wish  to 
find  it,  i.e.  in  vis  inertice,  in  some  blind  and 
accidental  mechanism  of  ideas,  in  automatic  and 
purely  passive  adaptation  and  modification,  in 
the  compulsory  action  of  adjustment  to  environ 
ment. 

Again,  in  his  attack  on  the  evolutionists'  so- 
called  '  struggle  for  existence/  of  which  I  shall 
speak  more  exhaustively  later,  it  is  the  suggestion 
that  life — mere  existence  in  itself — is  worthy  of 
being  an  aim  at  all,  that  he  deprecates  so  pro 
foundly.  And,  once  more,  it  is  with  the_  view 
of  elevating  man  and  his^  aspirations  that  he 
levels  the  attack. 

Whatever  we  may  think  of  his  methods, 
therefore,!  at  least  his  aim  was  sufficiently  lofty 
and  honourable,  and  we  must  bear  in  mind 
that  he  never  shirked  the  duties  which, /rightly 
or  wrongly,  he  imagined  would  help  him  to 
achieve  it. 

What  was  Nietzsche?  If  we  accept  his  own 
definition  of  the  philosopher's  task  on  earth,  we 
must  place  him  in  the  front  rank  of  philosophers. 
For,  according  to  him,  the  creation  of  new  values, 
new  principles,  new  standards,  is  the  philosopher's 

4 


LIFE  AND  WORKS 

sole  raison  d'etre ;  and  this  he  certainly  accom 
plished.  If,  on  the  other  hand,  with  all  the 
*  school '  philosophers,  we  ask  him  to  show  us 
his  system,  we  shall  most  surely  be  disappointed. 
In  this  respect,  therefore,  we  may  perhaps  need 
to  modify  our  opinion  of  him. 

Be  that  as  it  may,  it  is  safe  to  maintain  that 
he  was  a_  poet  of  no  mean  order ;  not  a  mere 
versifier  or  rhapsodist,  but  a  poet  in  the  old 
Greek  sense  of  the  word,  i.e.  a  maker.  In  our 
time  such  men  are  so  rare  I  that  we  are  apt  to 
question  whether  they  exist  at  all,  for  poetasters 
have  destroyed  our  faith  in  them.  Goethe  was 
perhaps  the  last  example  of  the  type  |  in  modern 
Europe,  and  although  we  may  recall  the  scientific 
achievements  of  men  like  Michelangelo,  Leonardo 
da  Vinci  and  Galileo,  we  are  not  sufficiently  ready 
to  associate  their  divining  and  intuitive  power 
in  the  department  of  science  jwith  their  purely 
artistic  and  poetic  achievements,  despite  the  fact 
that  the  two  are  really  inseparable. 

Knowing  the  high  authority  (with  which  poets 
of  this  order  |  are  wont  to  speak,  it  might  be 
supposed !  that  we  should  approach  Nietzsche's 
innovations  in  the  realm  of  science  I  with  some 
respect,'1  not  in  spite  of,  jbut  precisely  owing  to, 
his  great  poetic  genius.  Unfortunately  to-day 

5 


NIETZSCHE 

this  no  longer  follows.  Too  thoroughly  have  we 
divorced  science  jfrom  emotion  and  feeling  (very 
wrongly,  as  even  Herbert  Spencer  and  Buckle 
both  declared),  and  now,  wherever  we  see  emotion 
or  a  suggestion  of  passion,  we  are  too  apt  to 
purse  our  lips  and  stand  on  our  guard. 

When  we  consider  that  Nietzsche  was  ultimately 
to  prove  the  bitterest  enemy  of  Christianity,  and 
the  severest  critic  of 'the  ecclesiastic J  his  ante 
cedents  seem,  to  say  the  least,  remarkable.  His 
father,  Karl  Ludwig  Nietzsche,  born  in  1813, 
was  a  clergyman  of  the  German  Protestant 
Church ;  his  grandfather  had  also  taken  orders ; 
whilst  his  grandmother  on  his  father's  side  was 
descended  from  a  long  line  of  parsons.  Nor  do 
things  change  very  much  when  we  turn  to  his 
mother's  family;  for  his  maternal  grandfather, 
Oehler,  was  also  a  clergyman,  and,  according  to 
Nietzsche's  sister,  he  appears  to  have  been  a  very 
sound,  though  broad,  theologian. 

Yet,  perhaps,  it  is  we  who  are  wrong  in  seeing 
anything  strange  in  the  fact  that  a  man  with 
such  orthodox  antecedents  should  have  developed 
into  a  prophet  and  reformer  of  Nietzsche's  stamp ; 
for  we  should  remember  that  only  a  long  tradi 
tion  of  discipline  and  strict  conventionality,  lasting 
over  a  number  of  generations,  is  able  to  rear  that 

6 


LIFE  AND  WORKS 

will-power  and  determination  which,  as  the  lives 
of  most  great  men  have  shown,  are  the  first  con 
ditions  of  all  epoch-making  movements  started 
by  single  individuals. 

Friedrich  Nietzsche  was  born  at  Rocken  near 
Liitzen,  in  the  Prussian  province  of  Saxony,  on 
the  15th  of  October  1844.  From  his  earliest 
childhood  onwards  the  boy  seems  to  have  been 
robust  and  active  and  does  not  appear  to  have 
suffered  from  any  of  the  ordinary  ailments  of 
infancy.  In  the  biography  written  by  his  sister 
much  stress  is  laid  upon  this  fact,  while  the 
sometimes  exceptional  health  enjoyed  by  his 
parents  and  ancestors  is  duly  emphasised  by  the 
anxious  biographer.  Elisabeth  Nietzsche  (born 
in  July  1846),  the  biographer  in  question,  is 
perfectly  justified  in  establishing  these  facts  with 
care ;  for  we  know  that  our  poet  philosopher  died 
insane,  and  many  have  sought  to  show  that  his 
insanity  was  hereditary  and  could  be  traced 
throughout  his  works. 

Nietzsche's  father  died  in  1849,  and  in  the 
following  year  the  family  removed  to  Naumburg. 
There  the  boy  received  his  early  schooling,  first 
at  a  preparatory  school  and  subsequently  at 
the  Gymnasium — the  Grammar  School — of  the 
town.  As  a  lad,  it  is  said  that  he  was  fond  of 

7 


NIETZSCHE 

military  games,  and  of  sitting  alone,  and  it 
appears  that  he  would  recline  for  hours  at  his 
grandmother  Nietzsche's  feet,  listening  to  her 
reminiscences  of  the  great  Napoleon.  Towards 
the  end  of  1858  Mrs.  Nietzsche  was  offered  a 
scholarship  for  her  son,  for  a  term  of  six  years, 
in  the  Landes-Schule,  Pforta,  so  famous  for  the 
scholars  it  produced.  At  Pforta,  where  the  dis 
cipline  was  very  severe,  the  boy  followed  the 
regular  school  course  and  worked  with  great 
industry.  His  sister  tells  us  that  during  this 
period  he  distinguished  himself  most  in  his 
private  studies  and  artistic  efforts,  though  even 
in  the  ordinary  work  of  the  school  he  was 
decidedly  above  the  average.  It  was  here,  too, 
that  he  first  became  acquainted  with  Wagner's 
compositions,  and  a  word  ought  now  perhaps  to 
be  said  in  regard  to  his  musical  studies. 

Music,  we  know,  played  anything  but  a  minor 
role  in  his  later  life,  as  his  three  important 
essays,  Richard  Wagner  in  Bayreuth,  The  Case 
of  Wagner,  and  Nietzsche  contra  Wagner,  are 
with  us  to  prove.  I  fear,  however,  that  it  will 
be  impossible  to  go  very  deeply  into  this  question 
here,  save  at  the  cost  of  other  still  more  im 
portant  matters  which  have  a  prior  claim  to  our 
attention.  Let  i$  then  suffice  to  say  that,  as  a 

8 


LIFE  AND  WORKS 

boy,  Nietzsche's  talent  had  already  become  so 
noticeable  that  for  some  time  the  question  which 
agitated  the  elders  in  his  circle  of  relatives  and 
friends,  among  whom  were  some  competent 
judges,  was  whether  he  should  not  give  up  all 
else  in  order  to  develop  his  great  gift.  In  the 
end,  however,  it  was  decided  that  he  should 
become  a  scholar,  and  although  he  never  entirely 
gave  up  composing  and  playing  the  piano,  music 
never  attained  to  anything  beyond  the  dignity 
of  a  serious  hobby  in  his  life.  In  saying  this  I 
naturally  exclude  his  critical  writings  on  the 
subject,  which  are  at  once  valuable  and  im 
portant. 

Nietzsche's  six  years  at  Pforta  were  responsible 
for  a  large  number  of  his  subsequent  ideas. 
When  we  hear  him  laying  particular  stress  upon 
the  value  of  rigorous  training  free  from  all  senti 
mentality  ;  when  we  read  his  views  concerning 
austerity  and  the  importance  of  law,  order  and 
discipline,  we  must  bear  in  mind  that  he  is 
speaking  with  an  actual  knowledge  of  these 
things,  and  with  profound  experience  of  their 
worth.  The  excellence  of  his  philological  work 
may  also  be  ascribed  to  the  very  sound  training 
he  received  at  Pforta,  and  the  Latin  essay  which 
he  wrote  on  an  original  subject  (Theognis,  the 

9 


NIETZSCHE 

great  aristocratic  poet  of  Megara)  for  the  leaving 
examination,  laid  the  foundation  of  all  his  sub 
sequent  opinions  on  morality. 

Nietzsche  left  Pforta  in  September  1864  and 
entered  the  University  of  Bonn,  where  he  studied, 
philology  and  theology.  The  latter  he  aban 
doned  six  months  later,  however,  and  in  the 
autumn  of  1865  he  left  Bonn  for  Leipzig,  whither 
his  famous  teacher  Ritschl  had  preceded  him. 
Between  1865  and  1867  his  work  at  Leipzig 
proved  of  the  utmost  importance  to  his  career. 
Hellenism,  Schopenhauer  and  Wagner  now  entered 
into  his  life  and  became  paramount  influences 
with  him,  and  each  in  its  way  determined  what 
his  ultimate  mission  was  to  be.  Hellenism  drew 
him  ever  more  strongly  to  philology  and  to  the 
problem  of  culture  in  general;  Schopenhauer 
directed  him  to  philosophy,  and  Wagner  taught 
him  his  first  steps  in  a  subject  which  was  to  be 
the  actual  Leit-motif  of  his  teaching — I  refer  to 
the  question  of  Art. 

His  work  during  these  two  years,  arduous 
though  it  was,  in  no  way  affected  his  health,  and, 
despite  his  short-sight,  he  tells  us  that  he  was 
then  able  to  endure  the  greatest  strain  without 
the  smallest  trouble.  Being  of  a  robust  and 
energetic  nature,  however,  he  was  anxious  to  dis- 

10 


LIFE  AND  WORKS 

cover  some  means  of  employing  his  bodily  strength, 
and  it  was  for  this  reason  that,  regardless  of  the 
interruption  in  his  work,  he  was  enthusiastic  at 
the  thought  of  becoming  a  soldier. 

In  the  autumn  of  1867  he  entered  the  fourth 
regiment  of  Field  Artillery,  and  it  is  said  that 
he  performed  his  duties  to  the  complete  satis 
faction  of  his  superiors.  But,  alas,  this  lasted  but 
a  short  time ;  for,  as  the  result  of  an  unfortunate 
fall  from  a  restive  horse,  he  was  compelled  to 
leave  the  colours  before  he  had  completed  his 
term  of  service. 

In  October  1868,  after  a  serious  illness,  the 
student  returned  to  his  work  at  Leipzig,  and  now 
that  event  took  place  which  was  perhaps  the 
most  triumphant  and  most  decisive  in  his  career. 
It  was  Nietzsche's  ambition  to  get  his  doctor's 
degree  as  soon  as  possible  and  then  to  travel. 
Meanwhile,  however,  others  were  busy  determin 
ing  what  he  should  do.  Some  philological 
essays  which  he  had  written  in  his  student  days, 
and  which,  owing  to  their  excellence,  had  been 
published  by  the  '  Rheinisches  Museum/  had  at 
tracted  the  attention  of  the  educational  Board  of 
Bale.  One  of  the  Board  communicated  with 
Ritschl  concerning  Nietzsche,  and  the  reply  the 
learned  scholar  sent  was  so  favourable  that  the 
n 


NIETZSCHE 

University  of  Bale  immediately  offered  Ritschl's 
favourite  pupil  their  Professorship  of  Classical 
Philology.  This  was  an  exceptional  honour,  and, 
to  crown  it,  the  University  of  Leipzig  quickly 
granted  Nietzsche  his  doctor's  degree  without 
further  examination — truly  a  remarkable  occur 
rence  in  straitlaced  and  formal  Germany ! 

His  first  years  at  Bale  are  chiefly  associated  in 
our  minds  with  his  inaugural  address :  '  Homer 
and  Classical  Philology/  with  his  action  in  regard 
to  the  Franco-German  war,  and  with  his  lectures 
on  the 'Future  of  our  Educational  Institutions.' 
I  can  do  no  more  than  refer  to  these  here,  but 
as  regards  the  war  it  is  necessary  to  go  into 
further  detail. 

In  July  1870,  hostilities  opened  between  France 
and  Prussia.  Now,  although  Nietzsche  had  been 
forced  to  become  a  naturalised  Swiss  subject  in 
order  to  accept  his  appointment  at  Bale,  he  was 
loth  to  remain  inactive  while  his  own  country 
men  fought  for  the  honour  of  Germany.  He 
could  not,  however,  fight  for  the  Germans  with 
out  compromising  Switzerland's  neutrality.  He 
therefore  went  as  a  hospital  attendant,  and  in 
this  capacity,  after  obtaining  the  necessary  leave, 
he  followed  his  former  compatriots  to  the  war. 
According  to  Elisabeth  Nietzsche,  it  was  this  act 

12 


LIFE  AND  WORKS 

of  devotion  which  was  the  cause  of  all  her  brother's 
subsequent  ill-health.  In  Ars-sur-Moselle,  while 
tending  the  sick  and  wounded,  Nietzsche  con 
tracted  dysentery  from  those  in  his  charge.  With 
his  constitution  undermined  by  the  exertions  of 
the  campaign,  he  fell  very  seriously  ill,  and  had 
to  be  relieved  of  his  duties.  Long  before  he  was 
strong  enough  to  do  so,  however,  he  resumed  his 
work  at  Bale ;  and  now  began  that  second  phase 
of  his  life  during  which  he  never  once  recovered 
the  health  he  had  enjoyed  before  the  war. 

In  January  1872  Nietzsche  published  his  first 
book,  The  Birth  of  Tragedy.  It  is  really  but  a 
portion  of  a  much  larger  work  on  Hellenism  which 
he  had  always  had  in  view  from  his  earliest 
student  days,  and  it  may  be  said  to  have  been 
prepared  in  two  preliminary  lectures  delivered 
at  Bale,  under  the  title  of  the  'Greek  Musical 
Drama/  and  '  Spcratesjmd  Tragedj.'  The  work 
was  received  with  enthusiasm  by  Wagnerians; 
but  among  Nietzsche's  philological  friends  it 
succeeded  in  rousing  little  more  than  doubt  and 
suspicion.  It  was  a  sign  that  the  young  pro 
fessor  was  beginning  to  ascribe  too  much  import 
ance  to  Art  in  its  influence  upon  the  world,  and 
this  the  dry  men  of  science  could  not  tolerate. 

Between  1873  and  1876,  Nietzsche,  while  still 
13 


NIETZSCHE 

at  Bale,  published  four  more  essays  which,  for 
matter  and  form,  proved  to  be  among  the  most 
startling  productions  that  Germany  had  read  since 
Schopenhauer's  prime.  Their  author  called  these 
essays  Thoughts  out  of  Season,  and  his  aim  in 
writing  them  was  undoubtedly  the  regeneration 
of  German  culture.  The  first  was  an  attack  on 
German  Philistinism,  in  the  person  of  David 
Strauss,  the  famous  theologian  of  Tubingen, 
whom  Nietzsche  dubbed  the  'Philistine  of  Culture/ 
and  was  calculated  to  check  the  extreme  smug 
ness  which  had  suddenly  invaded  all  depart 
ments  of  thought  and  activity  in  Germany  as  the 
result  of  the  recent  military  triumph. 

The  second,  The  Use  and  Abuse  of  History, 
was  a  protest  against  excessive  indulgence  in  the 
'historical  sense,'  or  the  love  of  looking  back 
wards,  which  threatened  to  paralyse  the  intelli 
gence  of  Germany  in  those  days.  In  it  Nietzsche 
tries  to  show  how  history  is  for  the  few  and  not 
for  the  many,  and  points  out  how  rare  are  those 
who  have  the  strength  to  endure  the  lesson  of 
experience. 

In  the  third,  Schopenhauer  as  Educator,  Nietz 
sche  pits  his  great  teacher  against  all  other  dry- 
as-dust  philosophers  who  make  for  stagnation  in 
philosophy. 


LIFE  AND  WORKS 

The  fourth,  Richard  Wagner  in  Bayreuth, 
contains  Nietzsche's  last  word  of  praise  as  a 
friend  of  the  great  German  musician.  In  it  we 
already  see  signs  of  his  revulsion  of  feeling  ;  but 
on  the  whole  it  is  a  panegyric  written  with  love 
and  conviction. 

The  only  one  |of  the  four  Thoughts  out  of  Season 
(which  created  much  comment  ,'was  the  first,; con 
cerning  David  Strauss,  |and  this  gave  rise  to  a 
loud  outcry  against  (the  daring  young  philologist. 

Nietzsche  had  been  very  unwell  throughout 
this  period.  Dyspepsia  and  headaches,  brought 
on  partly  by  overwork,  racked  him  incessantly, 
and,  in  addition,  he  was  getting  ever  nearer  and 
nearer  to  a  final  and  irrevocable  breach  with  the 
greatest  friend  of  his  life  —  Richard  Wagner. 
After  obtaining  leave  from  the  authorities  he  went 
to  Sorrento,  where,  in  the  autumn  of  1876,  he 
began  work  on  his  next  important  book,  Human, 
All- too-human,  the  book  which  was  to  part  him 
for  ever  from  Wagner.  In  February  1878  the 
first  volume  was  ready  for  the  printer,  and  was 
published  almost  simultaneously  with  Wagners 
Parsifal,  which  work,  as  is  well  known,  was  the 
death-blow  to  Nietzsche's  faith  in  his  former 

idol 

In    Human,   All-too-human,   Nietzsche  as    a 

15 


NIETZSCHE 

philosopher  is  not  yet  standing  on  his  own  legs, 
as  it  were.  He  is  only  just  beginning  to  feel  his 
way,  and  is  still  deeply  immersed  in  the  thought 
of  other  men — more  particularly  that  of  the 
English  positivists.  As  a  work  of  transition, 
however,  Human,  All- too- Human  is  exceedingly 
interesting,  as  are  also  its  sequels  Miscellaneous 
Opinions  and  Apophthegms  (1879)  and  The 
Wanderer  and  his  Shadow  (1880).  But  in  none 
of  these,  as  the  author  himself  admits,  is  there 
to  be  found  that  certainty  of  aim  and  treatment 
which  characterised  his  later  writings, 

In  1879,  owing  to  ill-health,  Nietzsche  was 
compelled  to  resign  his  professorship  at  the 
University  of  Bale,  and  the  spring  of  that  year 
saw  him  an  independent  man  with  an  annual 
pension  of  3000  francs,  generously  granted  to  him 
by  the  Board  of  Management  on  the  acceptance 
of  his  resignation.  With  this  pension  and  a  small 
private  income  derived  from  a  capital  of  about 
£1400,  he  was  not  destitute,  though  by  no  means 
affluent,  and  when  we  remember  that  he  was 
obliged  to  defray  the  expenses  of  publication  in 
the  case  of  almost  every  one  of  his  books,  we  may 
form  some  idea  of  his  actual  resources. 

From  this  time  forward  Nietzsche's  life  was 
spent  in  travelling  and  writing.  Venice,  Marien- 

16 


LIFE  AND  WORKS 

bad,  Ziirich,  St.  Moritz  in  the  Ober-Engadine,  Sils 
Maria,  Tautenberg  in  Thuringia,  Genoa,  etc.,  etc. 
were  among  the  places  at  which  he  stayed,  ac 
cording  to  the  season  ;  and  during  the  year  1880 
his  health  materially  improved.  In  January  1881 
he  had  completed  the  manuscript  of  the  Dawn 
of  Day,  and  is  said  to  have  been  well  satisfied 
with  his  condition. 

In  the  Dawn  of  Day  Nietzsche  for  the  first 
time  begins  to  reveal  his  real  personality.  This 
book  is  literally  the  dawn  of  his  great  life  work, 
and  in  it  we  find  him  grappling  with  all  the 
problems  which  he  was  subsequently  to  tackle 
with  such  a  masterly  and  courageous  hand.  It 
appeared  in  July  1881  and  met  with  but  a  poor 
reception.  Indeed,  after  the  publication  of  the 
last  of  the  Thoughts  out  of  Season  Nietzsche 
appears  to  have  created  very  little  stir  among 
his  countrymen — a  fact  which,  though  it  greatly 
depressed  him,  only  made  him  redouble  his 
energies. 

In  September  1882  The  Joyful  Wisdom  was 
published — a  book  written  during  one  of  the 
happiest  periods  of  his  life.  It  is  a  veritable  fan 
fare  of  trumpets  announcing  the  triumphal  entry 
of  its  distinguished  follower  Zarathustra.  With 
it  Nietzsche's  final  philosophical  views  are 
B  '  17 


NIETZSCHE 

already  making  headway,  and  it  is  full  of 
the  love  of  life  and  energy  which  permeates  the 
grand  philosophical  poem  which  was  to  come 
after  it. 

Disappointed  by  the  meagre  success  of  his 
works,  and  hurt  by  the  attitude  of  various  friends, 
Nietzsche  now  retired  into  loneliness,  and,  settling 
down  on  the  beautiful  bay  of  Rapallo,  began  work 
on  that  wonderful  moral,  psychological,  and 
critical  rhapsody,  Thus  Spake  Zarathustra,  which 
was  to  prove  the  greatest  of  his  creations. 
During  the  years  1883-84,  the  three  first  parts 
of  this  work  were  published,  and,  though  each 
part  was  issued  separately  and  met  with  the  same 
cold  reception  which  had  been  given  to  his  other 
works  of  recent  years,  Nietzsche  never  once  lost 
heart  or  wavered  in  his  resolve.  It  required, 
however,  all  the  sublime  inspirations  which  we 
find  expressed  in  that  wonderful  Book  for  all 
and  None,  to  enable  a  man  to  stand  firmly  and 
absolutely  alone  amid  all  the  hardships  and 
reverses  that  beset  our  anchorite  poet  throughout 
this  period. 

It  was  about  this  time  that  Nietzsche  began  to 
take  chloral  in  the  hope  of  overcoming  his 
insomnia;  it  was  now,  too,  that  his  sister — the 
only  relative  for  whom,  despite  some  misunder- 

18 


LIFE  AND  WORKS 

standings,  lie  had  a  real  affection  —  became 
engaged  to  a  man  with  whom  he  was  utterly  out 
of  sympathy ;  and  all  the  while  negotiations,  into 
which  Nietzsche  had  entered  with  the  Leipzig 
University  for  the  purpose  of  securing  another 
professorial  chair,  were  becoming  ever  more 
hopeless. 

In  the  course  of  this  exposition  I  shall  have  to 
treat  of  the  doctrines  enunciated  in  Thus  Spake 
Zarathustra — indeed,  seeing  that  this  work  con 
tains  all  Nietzsche's  thought  in  a  poetical  form,  it 
would  be  quite  impossible  to  discuss  any  single 
tenet  of  his  philosophy  without  in  some  way 
referring  to  the  book  in  question.  I  cannot 
therefore  say  much  about  it  at  present,  save  that 
it  is  generally  admitted  to  be  Nietzsche'j3_o£>us 
magnum.  Besides  the  philosophical  views  ex 
pounded  in  the  four  parts  of  which  it  consists, 
the  value  of  its  autobiographical  passages  is 
enormous.  In  it  we  find  the  history  of  his  most 
intimate  experiences, !  friendships,  feuds, )  disap 
pointments,  triumphs,  :  and  the  like  ; '  and  the 
whole  is  written  in  a  style  so  magnetic  and 
poetical,  that,  as  a  specimen  of  belles-lettres 
alone,  entirely  apart  from  the  questions  it  treats, 
the  work  cannot  and  ought  not  to  be  overlooked. 

Although  there  is  now  scarcely  a  European 
19 


NIETZSCHE 

language  into  which  Zaraihustra  has  not  been 
translated,  although  the  fame  of  the  work,  at 
present,  is  almost  universal,  the  reception  it  met 
with  at  the  time  of  its  publication  was  so  unsatis 
factory,  and  misunderstanding  relative  to  its 
teaching  became  so  general,  that  within  a  year  of 
the  issue  of  its  first  part,  Nietzsche  was  already 
beginning  to  see  the  necessity  of  bringing  his 
doctrines  before  the  public  in  a  more  definite  and 
unmistakable  form.  During  the  years  that 
followed — that  is  to  say,  between  1883  and  1886 
— this  plan  was  matured,  and  between  1886  and 
1889— the  year  of  our  author's  final  breakdown, 
three  important  books  were  published  which  may 
be  regarded  as  prose-sequels  to  the  poem  Zara 
ihustra.  These  books  are :  Beyond  Good  and 
Evil  (1886),  The  Genealogy  of  Morals  (1887),  and 
The  Twilight  of  the  Idols  (1889);  while  the  post 
humous  works  The  Will  to  Power  (1901)  and  the 
little  volume  Antichrist,  published  in  1895,  when 
its  author  was  lying  hopelessly  ill  at  Naumburg, 
also  belong  to  the  period  in  which  Nietzsche 
wished  to  make  his  Zaraihustra  clear  and  com 
prehensible  to  his  fellows.  In  the  ensuing 
chapters  it  will  be  my  endeavour  to  state  briefly 
all  that  is  vital  in  the  works  just  referred  to. 
What  remains  to  be  related  of  Nietzsche's  life  is 
20 


LIFE  AND  WORKS 

sad  enough,  and  is  almost  common  knowledge. 
When  his  sister  Elizabeth  married  Dr.  Forster 
and  went  to  Paraguay  with  her  spouse,  Nietzsche 
was  practically  without  a  friend,  and,  had  it  not 
been  for  Peter  Gast's  devotion  and  help,  he  would 
probably  have  succumbed  to  his  constitutional 
and  mental  troubles  much  sooner  than  he  actually 
did.  Before  his  last  breakdown  in  Turin,  in 
January  1889,  the  only  real  encouragement  he  is 
ever  known  to  have  received  in  regard  to  his 
philosophical  works  came  to  him  from  Copenhagen 
and  Paris.  In  the  latter  city  it  was  Taine  who 
committed  himself  by  praising  Nietzsche,  and  in 
the  former  it  was  Dr.  George  Brandes,  a  clever 
and  learned  professor,  who  delivered  a  series  of 
lectures  on  the  new  message  of  the  German 
philosopher.  The  news  of  Brandes'  success  in, 
Copenhagen  in  1888  greatly  brightened  Nietz 
sche's  last  year  of  authorship,  and  he  corre 
sponded  with  the  Danish  professor  until  the  end. 
It  has  been  rightly  observed  that  these  lectures' 
were  the  dawn  of  Nietzscheism  in  Europe. 

As  the  result  of  over- work,  excessive  indulgence 
in  drugs,  and  a  host  of  disappointments  and 
anxieties,  Nietzsche's  great  mind  at  last  collapsed 
on  the  2nd  or  3rd  of  January  1889,  never  again 
to  recover. 

21 


NIETZSCHE 

The  last  words  he  wrote,  which  were  subse 
quently  found  on  a  slip  of  paper  in  his  study, 
throw  more  light  upon  the  tragedy  of  his  break 
down  than  all  the  learned  medical  treatises  that 
have  been  written  about  his  case.  *  I  am  taking 
narcotic  after  narcotic,'  he  said, '  in  order  to  drown 
my  anguish ;  but  still  I  cannot  sleep.  To-day  I 
will  certainly  take  such  a  quantity  as  will  drive 
me  out  of  my  mind/ 

From  that  time  to  the  day  of  his  death  (25th 
August  1900)  he  lingered  a  helpless  I  and  uncon 
scious  invalid,  first  in  the  care  of  his  aged 
mother,  and  ultimately,  when  Elizabeth  returned 
a  widow  from  Paraguay,  as  his  sister's  beloved 
charge. 

For  an  opinion  of  Nietzsche  during  his  last 
phase  I  cannot  do  better  than  quote  Professor 
Henri  Lichtenberger  of  Nancy,  who  saw  the 
invalid  in  1898 ;  and  with  this  sympathetic 
Frenchman's  valuable  observations,  I  shall  draw 
this  chapter  to  a  close  : — 

'  In  the  gradual  wane  of  this  enthusiastic  lover 
of  life,  of  this  apologist  of  energy,  of  this  prophet  of 
Superman  there  is  something  inexpressibly  sad — 
inexpressibly  beautiful  and  peaceful.  His  brow  is 
still  magnificent — his  eyes,  the  light  of  which 
seems  to  be  directed  inwards,  have  an  expression 

22 


LIFE  AND  WORKS 

which  is  indefinably  and  profoundly  moving. 
What  is  going  on  within  his  soul  ?  Nobody  can 
say.  It  is  just  possible  that  he  may  have  pre 
served  a  dim  recollection  of  his  life  as  a  thinker 
and  a  poet.' 


NIETZSCHE 


CHAPTER    II 

NIETZSCHE  THE   AMORALIST 

FROM  a  casual  study  of  Nietzsche's  life  it  might  be 
gathered  that  he  had  little  time  for  private 
meditation  or  for  any  lonely  brooding  over 
problems  foreign'  to  his  school  and  university 
studies.  Indeed,  from  the  very  moment  when  it 
was  decided  that  he  should  become  a  scholar,  to 
the  day  when  the  University  of  Leipzig  granted 
him  his  doctor's  degree  without  examination,  his 
existence  seems  to  have  been  so  wholly  occupied 
by  strenuous  application  to  the  duties  which  his 
aspirations  imposed  upon  him  that,  even  if  he  had 
had  the  will  to  do  so,  it  would  seem  that  he  could 
not  have  had  the  leisure  to  become  engaged  in 
any  serious  thought  outside  his  regular  work. 
Nevertheless,  if  we  inquire  into  the  matter  more 
deeply,  we  find  to  our  astonishment,  that  during 
the  whole  of  that  arduous  period — from  his 
thirteenth  to  this  twenty-fourth  year  —  his 
imagination  did  not  once  cease  from  playing 
24 


NIETZSCHE  THE  AMORALIST 

around  problems  of  the  highest  import,  quite  un 
related  to  his  school  and  university  subjects. 

In  the  introduction  to  The  Geneaology  of 
Morals,  he  writes  as  follows : — ' .  .  .  while  but  a 
boy  of  thirteen  the  problem  of  the  origin  of  evil 
haunted  me :  to  it  I  dedicated,  in  an  age  when 
we  have  in  heart  half-play,  half-God,  my  first 
literary  child-play,  my  first  philosophical  com 
position  ;  and,  as  regards  my  solution  of  the 
problem  therein,  well,  I  gave,  as  is  but  fair,  God 
the  honour,  and  made  him  Father  of  evil.' 1  And 
then  he  continues :  '  A  little  historical  and 
philological  schooling,  together  with  an  inborn 
and  delicate  sense  regarding  psychological  ques 
tions,  changed  my  problem  in  a  very  short  time 
into  that  other  one:  under  what  circumstances 
and  conditions  did  man  invent  the  valuations 
good  and  evil  ?  And  what  is  their  own  specific 
value?' 

This  problem,  as  stated  here,  seems  stupendous 
enough  ;  in  fact,  it  would  be  difficult,  in  the  whole 
realm  of  human  thought,  to  discover  a  question 
of  greater  moment  and  intricacy;  and  yet  we 
shall  see  that  Nietzsche  was  just  as  much  born 
to  attack  and  solve  it  as  Cardinal  Newman 
seems,  from  the  Apologia  pro  Vita  Sua, 

1  See  also  D.D.  Aph.  81. 
25 


NIETZSCHE 

to  have  been  born  to  the  Roman  Catholic 
Church. 

If  we  reflect  a  moment,  we  find  that  'good' 
and  'evil'  are  certainly  words  that  exercise  a 
tremendous  power  in  the  world.  To  attach  the 
word  '  good '  to  any  thing  or  deed  is  to  give  it 
the  hall-mark  of  desirability :  on  the  other  hand, 
to  attach  the  word  '  evil '  to  it  is  tantamount  to 
proscribing  it  from  existence.  Even  in  the  old 
English  proverb,  'Give  a  dog  a  bad  name  and 
hang  him,'  we  have  a  suggestion  of  the  enormous 
force  which  has  been  compressed  into  the  two 
monosyllables  'good'  and  'bad,'  and  before  we 
seriously  take  up  the  problem,  it  were  well  to 
ponder  a  while  over  the  really  profound  signifi 
cance  of  these  two  words. 

Nietzsche,  as  we  have  already  observed,  was 
never  in  any  doubt  as  to  their  importance :  his 
life  passion  was  the  desire  to  solve  the  meaning, 
the  origin,  and  the  intrinsic  value  of  the  two 
terms ;  and  he  did  not  rest  until  he  had  achieved 
his  end. 

Let  us  now  examine  what  morality — what 
'good'  and  'evil' — means  to  almost  everybody 
to-day.  In  the  minds  of  nearly  all  those  people 
who  are  neither  students  nor  actual  teachers  of 
philosophy,  there  is  a  superstition  that  'good* 
26 


NIETZSCHE  THE  AMORALIST 

is  a  perfectly  definite  and  absolute  value,  and 
that  'evil'  is  known  unto  all.  Few  seem  to 
doubt  that  the  meaning  of  these  words  has  been 
fixed  once  and  for  ever.  The  ordinary  European 
lives,  reads,  and  sleeps,  year  in,  year  out,  under 
the  delusion  that  all  is  quite  clear  in  regard  to 
right  and  wrong.  Such  a  person  is,  of  course, 
somewhat  abashed  when  you  tell  him  that  a 
certain  people  in  the  East  practise  infanticide  and 
call  it  good  or  that  a  certain  people  in  the  West 
always  separate  at  meals  and  eat  apart  and  call 
this  good.  He  usually  gets  over  the  difficulty, 
however,  by  saying  that  they  know  no  better, 
and  when  at  last  he  is  hard  pressed,  and  is  bound 
to  admit  that  views  of  good  and  bad,  sometimes 
the  reverse  of  his  own,  actually  do  preserve  and 
unite  people  in  strange  lands,  he  takes  refuge  in 
the  hope  that  all  differences  may  one  day  be 
broken  down  and  that  the  problem  will  thus  be 
solved. 

No  such  facile  shelving  of  the  question,  how 
ever,  could  satisfy  Nietzsche.  From  the  very 
outset  he  freed  himself  from  all  national  and 
even  racial  prejudices,  and  could  see  no  particular 
reason  why  the  kind  of  morality  now  prevailing 
in  Europe,  or  countries  like  Europe,  must 
necessarily  and  ultimately  overcome  and  supplant 
27 


NIETZSCHE 

all  others.  He  therefore  attacked  the  question 
with  a  perfectly  open  mind,  and  asked  himself 
whether  he  quite  understood  the  part  the  terms 
'good'  and  'evil'  have  played  in  human 
history. 

Is  morality — its  justification  in  our  midst  and 
its  mode  of  action — comprehended  at  all  ? — He 
replies  to  this  question  so  daringly  and  so  up 
rightly,  that  at  first  his  clearness  may  only 
bewilder  us. 

These  terms  '  good '  and  '  evil/  he  tells  us,  are 
merely  a  means  to  the  acquisition  of  power. 
And,  indeed,  in  the  very  resistance  we  offer  when 
he  attempts  to  criticise  our  notions  of  morality, 
we  tacitly  acknowledge  that  in  this  morality  our 
strength  does  actually  reside.  '  No  greater  power 
on  earth  was  found  by  Zarathustra  than  good 
and  evil ' 1  '  No  people  could  live  without  first 
valuing ;  if  a  people  will  maintain  itself,  however, 
it  must  not  value  as  its  neighbour  valueth.' 2 

In  the  last  sentence  we  have  seized  Nietzsche's 
clue  to  the  whole  question.  If  you  would  main 
tain  yourself,  you  cannot  and  must  not  value 
as  your  neighbour  values.  Good  and  evil,  then, 
are  not  permanent  absolute  values;  they  are 
transient,  relative  values,  serving  an  end  which 
1  £.,  p.  67.  a  Z.,  p.  65. 

28 


NIETZSCHE  THE  AMORALIST 

can  be  explained  in  terms  of  biology  and  anthro 
pology. 

But  now  let  us  halt  a  moment,  for  the  sake  of 
clearness,  and  let  us  inquire  precisely  how 
Nietzsche  himself  was  led  to  this  conclusion. 

In  the  summer  of  1864,  when  he  was  in  his 
twentieth  year,  he  was  given  some  home  work 
to  do  which  he  was  expected  to  have  ready  by 
the  end  of  the  holidays.  It  was  to  consist  of  a 
Latin  thesis  upon  some  optional  subject,  and  he 
chose  '  Theognis,  the  Aristocratic  Poet  of  Megara.' 

While  preparing  the  work  he  was  struck  with 
the  author's  use  of  the  words  '  good '  and  '  bad ' 
as  synonymous  with  aristocratic  and  plebeian, 
and  it  was  this  valuable  hint  which  first  set  him 
on  the  right  track.  Theognis  and  his  friends, 
being  desirous  of  making  their  power  prevail, 
were  naturally  compelled  to  regard  any  force 
which  assailed  that  power  as  bad — '  bad,'  in  the 
sense  of  *  dangerous  to  their  order  of  power ' ; 
and  thus  it  came  to  pass  that  Theognis,  as  an 
aristocrat  in  the  heat  of  a  struggle  between  an 
oligarchy  and  a  democracy,  spoke  of  the  demo 
cratic  values  as '  bad '  and  of  those  of  his  own  party 
as  '  good.' 

The  writing  of  this  essay  had  other  conse 
quences  which  I  shall  only  be  able  to  refer  to 
29 


NIETZSCHE 

in  the  next  chapter ;  but  at  present  let  it  suffice 
to  say  that,  in  recognising  the  arbitrary  use  made 
by  Theognis  of  the  epithets  good  and  bad 
in  designating  the  oligarchy  and  the  democracy 
respectively,  Nietzsche  was  first  induced  to  look 
upon  morality  merely  as  a  weapon  in  the  struggle 
for  power,  and  he  thus  freed  himself  from  all 
the  usual  bias  which  belongs  to  the  absolutist's 
standpoint.  Hence  his  claim  to  the  surname 
'  amoralist,'  and  his  use  of  the  phrase  '  Beyond 
Good  and  Evil,'  as  the  title  of  one  of  his  greatest 
works. 

Let  us,  however,  remember  that  although 
Nietzsche  did  undoubtedly  take  up  a  position 
beyond  good  and  evil,  in  order  to  free  himself 
temporarily  from  the  gyves  of  all  tradition,  still 
this  attitude  was  no  more  than  a  momentary  one, 
and  he  ultimately  became  as  rigid  a  moralist  as 
the  most  exacting  could  desire.  It  was  a  new 
.morality,  however,  or  perhaps  a  forgotten  one, 
which  he  ultimately  preached,  and  with  the  view  of 
preparing  the  ground  for  it  he  was  in  a  measure 
obliged  to  destroy  old  idols.  'He  who  hath  to 
be  a  creator  in  good  and  evil/  says  Zarathustra, 
'  verily,  he  hath  first  to  be  a  destroyer,  and  to 
break  values  to  pieces.' l 

1  z.t  p.  138. 
30 


NIETZSCHE  THE  AMORALIST 

Assuming  the  position  of  the  relativist,  then, 
Nietzsche  observed  that  all  morality,  all  use  of 
the  words  '  good '  and  '  evil/  is  only  an  artifice  for 
acquiring  power.  Turning  to  the  animal  king 
dom,  he  went  in  search  of  support  for  his  views, 
and  very  soon  discovered  that,  in  biology  at 
least,  no  fact  was  at  variance  with  his  general 
hypothesis. 

In  nature  every  species  of  organic  being  be 
haves  as  if  its  kind  alone  ought  ultimately  to 
prevail  on  earth,  and,  whether  it  try  to  effect 
this  end  by  open  aggression  or  cowardly  dissim 
ulation,  the  motive  in  both  cases  is  the  same. 
The  lion's  good  is  the  antelope's  evil.  If\the 
antelope  believed  the  lion's  good  to  be  its  good, 
it  would  go  and  present  itself  without  further 
ado  before  the  lion's  jaws.  If  the  lion  believed 
the  antelope's  good  to  be  its  good  it  would 
adopt  vegetarianism  forthwith  and  eschew  its 
carnivorous  habits  for  the  rest  of  its  days. 
Again,  no  parasite  could  share  the  notions  of 
good  and  evil  entertained  by  its  victim,  neither 
could  the  victims  share  the  notions  of  good  and 
evil  entertained  by  the  parasite.  Everywhere, 
then,  those  modes  of  conduct  are  adopted  and 
perpetuated  by  a  species,  which  most  conduce  to 
the  prevalence  and  extension  of  their  particular 


NIETZSCHE 

kind,  and  that  species  which  fails  to  discover  the 
class  of  conduct  best  calculated  to  preserve  and 
strengthen  it  gets  overcome  in  the  war  of  con 
duct  which  constitutes  the  incessant  struggle 
for  power. 

Now,  applying  the  knowledge  to  man,  what 
did  Nietzsche  find  ?  He  found  there  was  also  a 
war  being  waged  between  the  different  modes  of 
conduct  which  now  prevail  among  men,  and  that 
what  one  man  sets  up  as  good  is  called  evil  by 
another  and  vice  versa.  But  of  this  he  soon 
became  convinced,  that  whenever  and  wherever 
good  and  evil  had  been  set  up  as  absolute 
values,  they  had  been  thus  elevated  to  power  with 
the  view  of  preserving  and  multiplying  one 
specific  type  of  man. 

All  moralities,  therefore,  were  but  so  many 
Trades  Union  banners  flying  above  the  heads 
of  different  classes  of  men,  woven  and  upheld 
by  them  for  their  own  needs  and  aspirations. 

So  far,  so  good.  But  then,  if  that  were  so, 
the  character  of  a  morality  must  be  determined 
by  the  class  of  men  among  whom  it  came  into 
being. 

We  shall  see  that  Nietzsche  did  not  hesitate 
to  accept  this  conclusion,  and  that  if  for  a 
moment  he  declared :  '  No  one  knoweth  yet  what 


NIETZSCHE  THE  AMORALIST 

is  good  and  what  is  evil ! '  the  next  minute  he 
was  asking  himself  this  searching  question: 
'Is  our  morality — that  is  to  say,  the  particular 
table  of  values  which  is  gradually  modifying  us 
— compatible  with  an  ideal  worthy  of  man's  in 
heritance  and  past  ? ' 

If  Nietzsche  has  been  called  dangerous,  per 
nicious  and  immoral,  it  is  because  people  have 
deliberately  overlooked  this  last  question  of  his. 
No  thinker  who  states  and  honestly  sets  out 
to  answer  this  question,  as  Nietzsche  did,  de 
serves  to  be  slandered,  as  he  has  been  slandered, 
by  prejudiced  and  interested  people  intent  on 
misunderstanding  only  in  order  that  they  may 
fling  mud  more  freely. 

Nietzsche  cast  his  critical  eye  very  seriously 
around  him,  and  the  sight  of  the  modern  world 
led  him  to  ask  these  admittedly  pertinent  ques 
tions  :  '  Is  that  which  we  have  for  centuries  held 
for  good  and  evil,  really  good  and  evil  ?  Does 
our  table  of  ethical  principles  seem  to  be 
favouring  the  multiplication  of  a  desirable 
type  ? ' 

In  answering  these  two  inquiries,  Nietzsche 
unfortunately  stormed  the  most  formidable  strong 
holds  of  modern  society  —  Christianity  and 
Democracy ;  and  perhaps  this  accounts  for  the 
c  33 


NIETZSCHE 

fact  that  his  fight  was  so  uneven  and  so  hopeless. 
The  strength  of  modern  Europe,  if  indeed  there 
be  any  strength  in  her,  lies  precisely  on  the  side 
of  Christianity  and  Democracy,  the  grandmother 
and  the  mother  of  what  is  called  '  progress,' 
'  modernity ' ;  and  in  assailing  these,  Nietzsche 
must  have  known  that  he  was  engaging  in  a  hand- 
to-hand  struggle  with  stony-hearted  adversaries 
unaccustomed  to  giving  quarter  and  unscrupulous 
in  their  methods. 

Nietzsche  clearly  saw  that  if  all  moral  codes  are 
but  weapons  protecting  and  helping  to  universalise 
distinct  species  of  men,  then  the  Christian  re 
ligion  with  its  ethical  principles  could  be  no 
exception  to  the  rule.  It  must  have  been  created 
at  some  time  and  in  some  place  by  one  who  had 
the  interests  of  a  certain  type  of  man  at  heart, 
and  who  desired  to  make  that  type  paramount. 
Now  if  that  were  really  so,  the  next  question  that 
occurred  to  Nietzsche's  mercilessly  logical  mind 
was  this:  'Is  the  Christian  religion,  with  its 
morality,  tending  to  preserve  and  multiply  a 
desirable  type  of  man  ? ' 

To  this  last  question  Nietzsche  replies  most 
emphatically  'No!' 

But,  before  going  into  the  reasons  of  this  flat 
negative,  let  us  first  pause  to  consider  the  age  and 

34 


NIETZSCHE  THE  AMORALIST 

the  circumstances  in  which  our  author  wrote  and 
thought 

Long  before  Nietzsche  had  reached  his  prime 
David  Strauss  had  published  his  Life  of  Jesus ; 
in  1863,  when  Nietzsche  was  still  in  his  teens, 
Renan  published  his  Vie  de  Jesus,  and  in  the 
meantime  Charles  Darwin  had  given  his  Origin 
of  Species  to  the  world.  These  books  had  been 
read  by  a  Europe  that  had  already  studied  Hume 
and  Lamarck,  Kant  and  Schopenhauer,  and  in  all 
directions  a  fine  ear  could  not  help  hearing  the 
falling  timbers  of  Christian  dogma. 

In  the  midst  of  this  general  work  of  destruction 
it  was  almost  impossible  for  Nietzsche  to  remain 
unmoved  or  indifferent,  and  very  soon  he  found 
that  he  too  was  drawn  into  the  general  stream  of 
European  thought ;  but  only  to  prove  how  com 
pletely  he  was  independent  of  it,  and  in  every 
way  superior  to  it. 

He  contemplated  the  work  of  the  destroyers  for 
some  time  with  amused  interest;  and  then  it 
suddenly  occurred  to  him  to  inquire  whether 
these  zealous  and  well-meaning  housebreakers 
were  really  doing  any  lasting  good,  or  whether  all 
their  efforts  were  not  perhaps  a  little  misguided. 
True,  they  were  pulling  the  embellishments  from 
the  walls  and  were  casting  the  most  cherished 
35 


NIETZSCHE 

idols  of  the  Christian  Faith  into  the  dust.  But 
the  walls  themselves,  the  actual  design  of  the 
edifice,  remained  untouched  and  as  strong  as  ever. 
A  few  broken  stones,  a  few  complaints  from  the 
priestly  archaeologists  who  wished  to  preserve 
them,  and  then  all  the  noise  subsided !  Europe 
remained  as  it  was  before — that  is  to  say,  still  in 
possession  of  a  stronghold  of  Christianity,  merely 
divested  of  its  superflous  ornament. 

Nietzsche  soon  perceived  that,  in  spite  of  all 
the  rubbish  and  refuse  which  such  people  as  Kant, 
Schopenhauer,  Strauss,  Renan  and  others  had 
made  of  Christian  dogma,  the  essential  core  of 
Christianity,  the  vital  organ  of  its  body— its 
morality — had  so  far  remained  absolutely  intact. 
Nay,  he  saw  that  it  was  actually  being  plastered 
up  and  restored  by  scholars  and  men  of  science 
who  vowed  that  they  could  proffer  reasonable, 
rationalistic,  and  logical  grounds  in  support  of  it. 

Just  as  Christian  dogma  and  metaphysics  had 
been  rationalised  and  philosophically  proved  by 
the  scholars  of  the  Middle  Ages,  and  even  as  late 
as  Leibnitz ;  so,  now,  Christian  morality  was  being 
presented  in  a  purely  philosophical  garb  by  the 
intellects  of  Europe. 

Having  relinquished  the  dogma  as  no  longer 
tenable,  all  scholars  and  men  of  science  were  try- 

36 


NIETZSCHE  THE  AMORALIST 

ing  with  redoubled  vigour  to  bolster  up  Christian 
ethics  with  elaborate  text-books  and  learned 
treatises.  There  were  some  who  accepted  it  all 
as  if  it  were  innate  in  human  nature,  and  attributed 
it  to  a  '  moral  sense ' ;  there  were  others — good- 
natured  biologists — who  were  likewise  desirous  of 
leaving  it  whole,  and  who  declared  with  conviction 
that  it  was  the  natural  outcome  of  the  feelings  of 
pleasure  and  pain  ;  and  there  were  yet  others  who 
assumed  that  it  must  have  been  evolved  quite 
automatically  out  of  expediency  and  non- 
expediency. 

Not  one  of  these  would-be  rationalists,  however, 
halted  at  the  Christian  terms  '  good '  and  '  bad ' 
themselves,  in  order  to  ask  himself  whether,  like 
all  the  other  notions  of  good  and  evil  prevailing 
elsewhere  under  the  shelter  of  other  religions, 
these,  the  Christian  notions,  might  not  have  been 
invented  at  some  particular  time  by  a  certain 
kind  of  man,  simply  with  the  view  of  preserving 
and  universalising  his  specific  type.  Breathless 
from  their  efforts  at  getting  rid  of  the  dogma,  they 
did  not  dream  that  perhaps  the  most  important 
part  of  the  work  still  remained  to  be  done. 

Nietzsche  went  to  the  very  foundation  of  the 
Christian  edifice.  He  pointed  to  its  morality  and 
said :  if  we  are  going  to  measure  the  value  of  this 

37 


NIETZSCHE 

religion,  let  us  cease  our  petty  quarrels  concern 
ing  the  truth  or  falsehood  of  such  stories  as  the 
loss  of  the  Gadarene  swine,  or  the  miracle  of  the 
loaves  and  fishes,  and  let  us  throw  the  whole  of 
Christian  morality  into  the  scales  and  appraise  its 
precise  worth  as  a  system  of  ethics.  Nietzsche 
would  have  scorned  to  quarrel  with  the  Church, 
as  Huxley  did ;  for  much  more  important  issues 
were  at  stake.  The  worth  of  a  religion  is  measured 
by  its  morality ;  because  by  its  morality  it  moulds 
and  rears  men  and  reveals  the  type  of  man  who 
ultimately  wishes  to  prevail  by  means  of  it. 

With  the  metaphysics  and  the  dogma  of 
Christianity  in  ruins  all  around  him,  therefore, 
Nietzsche  took  a  step  very  far  in  advance  of  the 
rationalistic  iconoclasts  of  his  age.  He  attacked 
Christian  morals,  and  declared  them  to  be,  like 
all  other  morals,  merely  a  weapon  in  the  hands  of 
a  certain  type  of  man,  with  which  that  type 
struggled  for  power. 

But  bold  as  this  step  was,  it  constituted  but 
the  first  of  a  series,  the  next  of  which  was  to  dis 
cover  the  type  which  had  laid  the  foundations  of 
the  Christian  ideal.  If  it  could  be  proved  that 
these  Christian  values  had  been  created  by  a 
noble  species  with  the  object  of  perpetuating  that 
species,  then  Christianity  would  come  forth  from 
5* 


NIETZSCHE  THE  AMORALIST 

the  inquiry  vindicated  to  the  hilt,  and  all  the 
damage  done  to  its  dogma  would  not  have  de 
terred  Nietzsche  from  standing  by  it  and  uphold- 
it  to  his  very  last  breath.  Alas  !  Things  turned 
out  somewhat  differently  and  Nietzsche  was  not 
by  any  means  the  least  pained  by  the  result. 
Pursuing  the  inquiry  with  his  usual  unflinching 
and  uncompromising  honesty,  and  avoiding  no 
conclusion  however  unpleasant  or  fatal,  Nietzsche, 
the  scion  of  a  profoundly  religious  house,  the 
lover  of  order  and  tradition,  with  the  blood  of 
generations  of  earnest  believers  in  his  veins, 
finally  found  himself  compelled  to  renounce  and 
even  to  condemn,  root  and  branch,  the  faith  which 
had  been  the  strength  and  hope  of  his  forebears. 

Before  turning  to  the  next  chapter,  where  I 
shall  explain  how  he  came  to  regard  this  step  as 
inevitable,  it  should  be  said  concerning  Nietzsche's 
philosophy  in  general,  that  it  is  essentially  and 
through  and  through  religious  and  almost  pro 
phetic  in  spirit.  No  careful  reader  of  his  works 
can  doubt  that  Nietzsche  was  a  deeply  religious 
man.  A  glance  at  Thus  Spake  Zarathustra 
alone  would  convince  any  one  of  this ;  while  in 
his  constant  references  to  religion  throughout  his 
works,  as  '  a  step  to  higher  intellectuality/ l  as  '  a 
1  o.  K,p.  81. 
39 


NIETZSCHE 

means  to  invaluable  contentedness/1  as  'a  measure 
of  discipline,' 2  as  a  powerful  social  factor,3  a  more 
substantial  confirmation  of  the  fact  is  to  be  found. 

It  is  well  to  bear  in  mind,  however,  throughout 
our  study  of  Nietzsche,  that  he  had  a  higher  type 
always  in  view ;  that  he  was  also  well  aware  that 
this  type  could  only  be  attained  by  the  strict 
observance  of  a  new  morality,  and  that  if  he 
opposed  other  forms  of  morality — more  parti 
cularly  the  Christian  form — it  was  because  he 
earnestly  believed  that  they  were  rearing  an 
undesirable  and  even  despicable  kind  of  man. 

'  Yerily  men  have  made  for  themselves  all  their 
good  and  evil.  Verily  they  did  not  take  it :  they 
did  not  find  it :  it  did  not  come  down  as  a  voice 
from  heaven/4 

'  Behold,  the  good  and  just !  Whom  do  they 
hate  most  ?  Him  who  breaketh  up  their  tables  of 
values ;  the  breaker,  the  law-breaker :  he,  however, 
is  the  creator.' 6 

'  Verily  a  muddy  stream  is  man.  One  must  be 
at  least  a  sea  to  be  able  to  absorb  a  muddy  stream 
without  becoming  unclean/ 

'  Behold,  I  teach  you  Superman :  he  is  that 
sea ;  in  him  your  great  contempt  can  sink.' 6 

1  O.  E.t  p.  81.    &G.  E.,  p.  80.     3  G.  M.,  3rd  Essay.,  Aph.  15. 
4  Z.,  p.  67.  •  Z.,  p.  20.  6  Z.,  p.  8. 

40 


NIETZSCHE  THE  MORALIST 


CHAPTER   III 

NIETZSCHE  THE  MORALIST 

CONCEIVING  all  forms  of  morality  to  be  but 
weapons  in  the  struggle  for  power,  Nietzsche  con 
cluded  that  every  species  of  man  must  at  some 
time  or  other  have  taken  to  moralising,  and  must 
have  called  that  'good'  which  its  instincts 
approved,  and  that  'bad'  which  its  enemies' 
instincts  approved.  In  Beyond  Good  and  Evil,1 
however,  he  tells  us  that  after  making  a  careful 
examination  '  of  the  finer  and  coarser  moralities 
which  have  hitherto  prevailed  or  still  prevail  on 
earth/  he  found  certain  traits  recurring  so  re 
gularly  together,  and  so  closely  connected  with 
one  another,  that,  finally,  two  primary  types  of 
morality  revealed  themselves  to  him.  That  is  to 
say,  after  passing  the  known  moralities  of  the 
world  in  review,  he  was  able  to  classify  them 
broadly  into  two  types. 

1  A  ph.  260. 

41 


NIETZSCHE 

He  observed  that  throughout  human  history 
there  had  been  a  continual  and  implacable  war 
between  two  kinds  of  men ;  it  must  have  begun 
in  the  remotest  ages,  and  it  continues  to  this  day. 
It  is  the  war  between  the  powerful  and  the  im 
potent,  the  strong  and  the  weak,  the  givers  and 
the  takers,  the  healthy  and  the  sick,  the  happy 
and  the  wretched.  The  powerful  formed  their 
concept  of  'good,'  and  it  was  one  which  justified 
their  strongest  instincts.  The  impotent  likewise 
acquired  their  view  of  the  matter,  which  was 
often  precisely  the  reverse  of  the  former  view. 

In  this  way  Nietzsche  arrived  at  the  follow 
ing  broad  generalisation  :  that  all  the  moralities  of 
the  world  could  be  placed  under  one  of  two  heads, 
Master  Morality  or  Slave  Morality. 

In  the  first,  the  master  morality,  it  is  the  oak 
which  contends :  I  must  reach  the  sun  and  spread 
broad  branches  in  so  doing;  this  I  call  'good,' 
and  the  herd  that  I  shelter  may  also  call  it  good. 
In  the  second,  the  slave  morality,  it  is  the  shrub 
which  says :  I  also  want  to  reach  the  sun,  these 
broad  branches  of  the  oak,  however,  keep  the 
sun  from  me,  therefore  the  oak's  instincts  are 
'bad/ 

It  is  obvious  that  these  two  points  of  view  exist 
and  have  existed  everywhere  on  earth.  Apart 
42 


NIETZSCHE  THE  MORALIST 

from  national  and  racial  distinctions,  mankind 
does  fall  into  the  two  broad  classes  of  master  and 
slave,  or  ruler  and  subject.  We  also  know  that 
each  of  these  classes  must  have  developed  its 
moral  code,  and  must  have  tried  to  protect  its 
conduct  and  life  therewith.  But,  what  we  did  not 
know  until  Nietzsche  pointed  the  fact  out  to  us, 
was :  which  morality  is  the  more  desirable  and 
the  more  full  of  promise  for  the  future  ?  Admit 
ting  that  the  master  and  the  slave  moralities  are 
struggling  for  supremacy  still,  which  of  them 
ought  we  to  promote  with  every  means  in  our 
power? — which  of  them  is  going  to  make  life 
more  attractive,  more  justifiable,  and  more  accept 
able  on  earth  ? 

These  are  now  questions  of  the  utmost  import 
ance;  because  it  is  precisely  now  that  pessimism, 
nihilism,  and  other  desperate  faiths  are  beginning 
to  set  their  note  of  interrogation  to  human  exist 
ence,  and  to  shake  our  belief  even  in  the  desir 
ability  of  our  own  survival. 

It  is  now  time  for  us  to  discover  whence  arises 
this  contempt  and  horror  of  life,  and  to  lay  the 
blame  for  it  either  at  the  door  of  the  master  or 
of  the  slave  morality. 

In  order  that  we  may  understand  how  to  set 
forth  upon  this  inquiry,  let  us  first  form  a  mental 
43 


NIETZSCHE 

image  of  the  two  codes  as  they  must  have  been 
evolved  by  their  originators. 

Nietzsche  reminds  us  before  we  start,  however,1 
that  in  most  communities  the  two  moralities  have 
become  so  confused  and  mingled,  in  order  to 
establish  that  compromise  which  is  so  dear  to  the 
hearts  of  the  peaceful,  that  it  would  be  almost  a 
hopeless  task  to  seek  any  society  on  earth  in 
which  they  are  now  to  be  seen  juxtaposed  in 
sharp  contrast.  Be  this  as  it  may,  in  order  to 
recognise  the  blood  of  each  when  we  come  across 
it,  we  have  only  to  think  of  what  must  have 
occurred  when  the  ruling  caste  and  the  ruled 
class  took  to  moralising. 

Taking  the  ruling  caste  first,  it  is  clear  that  in 
their  morality,  all  is  good  which  proceeds  from 
strength,  power,  health,  well-constitutedness,  hap 
piness,  and  awfulness ;  for  the  motive  force  behind 
the  people  who  evolved  it  was  simply  the  will  to 
discharge  a  plenitude,  a  superabundance,  of 
spiritual  and  physical  wealth.  A  consciousness 
of  high  tension,  of  a  treasure  that  would  fain  give 
and  bestow, — this  is  the  mental  attitude  of  the 
nobles.  The  antithesis  '  good '  and  '  bad '  to  this 
first  class  means  the  same  as  'noble'  and 
'  despicable.'  '  Bad '  in  the  master  morality  must 
1  O.  E,,  p.  227. 
44 


NIETZSCHE  THE  MORALIST 

be  applied  to  the  coward,  to  all  acts  that  spring 
from  weakness,  to  the  man  with  '  an  eye  to  the 
main  chance,'  who  would  forsake  everything  in 
order  to  live. 

The  creator  of  the  master  morality  was  he  who, 
out  of  the  very  fulness  of  his  soul,  transfigured  all 
he  saw  and  heard,  and  declared  it  better,  greater, 
more  beautiful  than  it  appeared  to  the  creator  of 
the  slave  morality.  Great  artists,  great  legislators, 
and  great  warriors  belong  to  the  class  that  created 
master  morality. 

Turning  now  to  the  second  class,  we  must  bear 
in  mind  that  it  is  fhe  product  of  a  community  in 
which  the  struggle  for  existence  is  the  prime  life- 
motor.  There1;  inasmuch  as  oppression,  suffering, 
weariness,  and  servitude  are  the  general  rule,  all 
will  be  regarded  as  good  that  tends  to  alleviate 
pain.  yPity,  the  obliging  hand,  the  warm  heart, 
patience,  industry,  and  humility, — these  are  un 
doubtedly  the  virtues  we  shall  here  find  elevated 
to  the  highest  places;  because  they  are  useful 
virtues ;  they  make  life  endurable ;  they  are  help 
ful  in  the  struggle  for  existence.  To  this  class, 
all  that  proceeds  from  strength,  superabundance 
of  spiritual  or  bodily  power,  or  great  health,  is 
looked  upon  with  loathing  and  mistrust,  while 
that  which  is  awful  is  the  worst  and  greatest  evil. 
45 


NIETZSCHE 

He  is  good  who  is  amenable,  kind,  unselfish,  meek, 
and  submissive ;  that  is  why,  in  all  communities 
where  slave  morality  is  in  the  ascendant,  a  '  good 
fellow '  always  suggests  a  man  in  possession  of  a 
fair  modicum  of  foolishness  and  sentimentality. 

The  creator  of  slave-morality  was  one  who,  out 
of  the  poverty  of  his  soul,  transfigured  all  he  saw 
and  heard,  and  declared  it  smaller,  meaner,  and 
less  beautiful  than  it  appeared  to  the  creator  of 
the  master  values.  Great  misanthropists,  pessi 
mists,  demagogues,  tasteless  artists,  nihilists, 
spiteful  authors  and  dramatists,  and  resentful 
saints  belong  to  the  class  that  created  slave- 
morality. 

The  first  order  of  values  are  active,  creative, 
Dionysiac.  The  second  are  passive,  defensive, 
venomous,  subterranean ;  to  them  belong  'Adapta 
tion/  'adjustment,'  and  'utilitarian  relationship 
to  environment.' 

Now,  seeing  that  mankind  is  undoubtedly 
moulded  by  the  nature  of  the  values  which 
prevail  over  it,  it  is  manifestly  of  paramount  im 
portance  to  the  philosopher  to  know  which  order 
of  values  conduces  to  rear  the  most  desirable 
species  of  man,  and  then  to  advocate  that  order, 
with  all  the  art  and  science  at  his  disposal. 

Nietzsche  saw  two  lines  of  life:  an  ascending 


NIETZSCHE  THE  MORALIST 

and  a  descending  line.  At  the  end  of  the  one  he 
pictured  an  ideal  type,  robust  in  mind  and  body, 
rich  enough  in  spirit  and  vigour  to  make  giving 
and  bestowing  a  necessary  condition  of  its  exist 
ence  ;  at  the  end  of  the  other  line  he  already  per 
ceived  degeneracy,  poverty  of  blood  and  spirit, 
and  a  sufficiently  low  degree  of  vitality  to  make 
parasitism  a  biological  need. 

He  believed  that  the  first,  or  noble  morality, 
when  it  prevailed,  made  for  an  ascending  line  of 
life  and  therefore  favoured  the  multiplication  of  a 
desirable  type  of  man ;  and  he  was  now  equally 
convinced  that  whenever  ignoble  or  slave  morality 
was  supreme,  life  not  only  tended  to  follow  the 
descending  line,  but  that  the  very  men  whose 
existence  it  favoured  were  the  least  likely  to  stem 
the  declining  tide.  Hence  it  seemed  to  him  that 
the  most  essential  of  all  tasks  was  to  ascertain 
what  kind  of  morality  now  prevailed,  in  order 
that  we  might  immediately  transvalue  our  values, 
while  there  was  still  time,  if  we  believed  this 
change  to  be  necessary. 

What  then  are  our  present  values  ?  Nietzsche 
replies  most  emphatically — they  are  Christian 
values. 

In  the  last  chapter  we  saw  that  although 
Christian  dogma  was  very  rapidly  becoming  mere 

47 


NIETZSCHE 

wreckage,  its  most  earnest  opposers  and  destroyers 
nevertheless  clung  with  fanatical  faith  to  Chris 
tian  morality.  Thus,  in  addition  to  the  vast 
multitude  of  those  professing  the  old  religion, 
there  was  also  a  host  of  atheists,  agnostics, 
rationalists,  and  materialists,  who,  as  far  as 
Nietzsche  was  concerned,  could  quite  logically  be 
classed  with  those  who  were  avowedly  Christian. 
And,  as  for  the  remainder — a  few  indifferent  and 
perhaps  nameless  people,  —  what  could  they 
matter?  Even  they,  perhaps,  if  hard  pressed, 
would  have  betrayed  a  sneaking,  cowardly  trust 
in  Christian  ethics,  if  only  out  of  a  sense  of 
security;  and  with  these  the  total  sum  of  the 
civilised  world  was  fully  made  up. 

Perhaps  to  some  this  may  appear  a  somewhat 
sweeping  conclusion.  To  such  as  doubt  its 
justice,  the  best  advice  that  can  be  given  is  to 
urge  them  to  consult  the  literature,  ethical,  philo 
sophical,  and  otherwise,  of  those  writers  whom 
they  would  consider  most  opposed  to  Christianity 
before  the  publication  of  Nietzsche's  works ;  and 
they  will  then  realise  that,  with  very  few  excep 
tions,  mostly  to  be  found  among  uninfluential  and 
uncreative  iconoclasts,  the  whole  of  the  Western 
civilised  world  in  Nietzsche's  time  was  firmly 
Christian  in  morals,  and  most  firmly  so,  perhaps, 


NIETZSCHE  THE  MORALIST 

in  those  very  quarters  where  the  dogma 
of  the  religion  of  pity  was  most  honestly 
disclaimed. 

It  had  therefore  become  in  the  highest  degree 
necessary  to  put  these  values  under  the  philo 
sophical  microscope,  and  to  discover  to  which 
order  they  belonged.  Was  Christianity  the  pur 
veyor  of  a  noble  or  of  a  slave  morality  ?  The  reply 
to  this  question  would  reveal  the  whole  tendency 
of  the  modern  world,  and  would  also  answer 
Nietzsche's  searching  inquiry :  '  Are  we  on  the 
right  track  ? ' 

Pursuing  Nietzsche's  method  as  closely  as  we 
can,  let  us  now  turn  to  Christianity,  as  we  find 
it  to-day,  and  see  whether  it  is  possible  to  bring 
its  values  into  line  with  one  of  the  two  broad 
classes  spoken  of  in  this  chapter. 

In  the  first  place,  Nietzsche  discovers  that 
Christianity  is  not  a  world-approving  faith.  The 
very  pivot  upon  which  it  revolves  seems  to  be  the 
slandering  and  depreciating  of  this  world,  together 
with  the  praise  and  exaltation  of  a  hypothetical 
world  to  come.  To  his  mind  it  seems  to  draw 
odious  comparisons  between  the  things  of  this 
earth  and  the  blessings  of  heaven.  Finally,  it 
gushes  in  a  very  unsportsmanlike  manner  over 
an  imaginary  beyond,  to  the  detriment  and  dis- 
D  49 


NIETZSCHE 

advantage  of  a  '  here/  of  this  earth,  of  this  life, 
and  posits  another  region — a  nether  region — for 
the  accommodation  of  its  enemies.1 

What,  now,  is  the  mental  attitude  of  these 
'  backworldsmen,'  as  Nietzsche  calls  them,  who 
can  see  only  the  world's  filth  ?  Who  is  likely  to 
need  the  thought  of  a  beyond,  where  he  will  live 
in  bliss  while  those  he  hates  will  writhe  in  hell  ? 
Such  ideas  occur  only  to  certain  minds.  Do  they 
occur  to  the  minds  of  those  who,  by  the  very 
health,  strength,  and  happiness  that  is  in  them, 
transfigure  all  the  world — even  the  ugliness  in  it 
— and  declare  it  to  be  beautiful  ?  Do  they  occur 
to  the  powerful  who  can  chastise  their  enemies 
while  their  blood  is  still  up  ?  Admitting  that 
the  world  may  be  surveyed  from  a  hundred 
different  standpoints,  is  this  particular  standpoint 
which  we  now  have  under  our  notice,  that  of  a 
contented,  optimistic,  sanguine  type,  or  that  of 
a  discontented,  pessimistic,  ansemic  one  ? 

'  To  the  pure  all  things  are  pure !  —I,  however, 
say  unto  you:  To  the  swine  all  things  are 
swinish.' 2 

Nietzsche's  sensitive  ear  caught  curious  notes 
in  the  daily  dronings  of  those  around  him — notes 

1  John  xii.  25  ;  1  John  ii.  15,  16 ;  James  iv.  4. 

2  Z.,  p.  249. 

SO 


NIETZSCHE  THE  MORALIST 

that  made  him  suspicious  of  the  whole  melody 
of  modern  life,  and  still  more  suspicious  of  the 
chorus  executing  it. 

He  heard  to  his  astonishment:  .  .  .  'the 
wretched  alone  are  the  good ;  the  poor,  the  im 
potent,  the  lowly  alone  are  good ;  only  the 
sufferers,  the  needy,  the  sick,  the  ugly  are  pious ; 
only  they  are  godly;  them  alone  blessedness 
awaits — but  ye,  the  proud  and  potent,  ye  are  for 
aye  and  evermore  the  wicked,  the  cruel,  the  lust 
ful,  the  insatiable,  the  godless ;  ye  will  also  be,  to 
all  eternity,  the  unblessed,  the  cursed,  and  the 
damned.' 1 

He  continued  listening  intently,  and,  with  his 
ear  attuned  anew,  these  sentiments  broke  strangely 
upon  his  senses : — 

'Blessed  are  the  poor  in  spirit:  for  theirs  is 
the  Kingdom  of  Heaven. 

'Blessed  are  they  that  mourn:  for  they  shall 
be  comforted. 

'  Blessed  are  the  meek :  for  they  shall  inherit 
the  earth. 

'  Blessed  are  the  peacemakers  :  for  they  shall 
be  called  the  children  of  God.' 2 

There  was  no  time  for  brooding  over  stray 
thoughts;  there  was  still  much  to  be  seen  and 

1  O.  M.t  1st  Essay,  Aph.  7.  2  Matthew  r. 

51 


NIETZSCHE 

heard.  When  you  want  to  catch  some  one  nap 
ping,  you  keep  your  eye  eagerly  upon  him,  and 
turn  neither  to  the  right  nor  to  the  left.  Nietz 
sche,  it  must  be  remembered,  was  at  this  stage 
treading  softly  towards  Europe  whom  he  believed 
to  be  c  napping.' 

In  his  lonely  hermit  cell  he  was  able  to  catch 
all  the  sounds  that  rose  from  the  city  beneath 
him,  and  he  heard  perhaps  more  than  the  in 
habitants  themselves. 

He  could  see  them  all  fighting  and  quarrelling, 
and  he  was  cheered,  because  he  knew  that  where 
the  great  fight  for  power  ceases,  the  standard  of 
life  falls.  But  some  he  saw  were  wounded,  others 
were  actually  unfit  for  the  battlefield,  a  large 
number  looked  tired  and  listless,  and  there  were 
yet  others — a  goodly  multitude — who  were  re 
sentful  at  the  sight  of  their  superiors  and  who, 
like  sulky  children,  dropped  their  arms  in  a  pet 
and  declared  that  they  would  not  play  any  more. 
And  what  were  all  these  feeble  and  less  viable 
mortals  doing  ?  They  were  crying  aloud,  and 
making  their  deepest  wishes  known.  They 
were  elevating  their  desiderata  to  the  highest 
places  amongst  earthly  virtues  —  and  driving 
back  the  others  with  words  \  Nietzsche  thought 
of  Reynard  the  Fox,  who,  at  the  very  moment 

52 


NIETZSCHE  THE  MORALIST 

that  he  was  about  to  be  hanged,  and  with 
the  rope  already  round  his  neck,  succeeded  by 
his  dialectical  skill  in  persuading  the  crowd 
to  release  him.  For  Nietzsche  could  hear  the 
weary,  the  wounded,  and  the  incapable  of  the 
fight,  crying  quite  distinctly  through  their  lips 
parched  for  rest :  '  Peace  is  good  !  Love  is  good  ! 
Love  for  one's  neighbour  is  good  !  Ay,  and  even 
love  for  one's  enemy  is  good  ! ' 1 

And  some  cried :  '  It  is  God  that  avengeth  me ! ' 
to  those  who  oppressed  them,  and  others  said: 
'  The  Lord  avenge  me ! ' 2 

Whereupon  Nietzsche  thought  of  the  Jehovah 
of  the  Old  Testament,  the  God  of  revenge  and 
thunderbolts ;  he  recalled  the  sentiment :  '  Ye 
shall  chase  your  enemies  and  they  shall  fall 
before  you  by  the  sword/  and  he  wondered  how 
this  had  come  to  mean  '  love  your  enemies/  in 
the  New  Testament.  Had  another  type  of 
men  perhaps  made  themselves  God's  mouth 
piece  ? 

Yes,  that  must  be  so ;  for,  in  their  holy  book, 
he  caine  across  this  passage,  ascribed  to  one  of 
their  greatest  saints : 

1  Matthew  xxiii.  39 ;  Mark  xiii.  31  ;  Luke  x.  27  ;  Matthew 
v.  44. 

8  Luke  xviii.  7,  8  ;  Romans  xii.  19 ;  Revelation  vi.  10. 

53 


NIETZSCHE 

'  Hath  not  God  made  foolish  the  wisdom  of 
this  world  ? 

'For  after  that  in  the  wisdom  of  God  the 
world  by  wisdom  knew  God,  it  pleased  God  by 
the  foolishness  of  preaching  to  save  them  that 
believe. 

'.  .  .  .  Not  many  wise  men  after  the  flesh, 
not  many  mighty,  not  many  noble  are  called : 

( But  God  hath  chosen  the  foolish  things  of  the 
world  to  confound  the  wise  :  and  God  hath  chosen 
the  weak  things  of  the  world  to  confound  the 
things  which  are  mighty  : 

'  And  base  things  of  the  world,  and  things 
which  are  despised,  hath  God  chosen,  yea  and 
things  which  are  not,  to  bring  to  nought  things 
that  are.'  * 

Here,  Nietzsche  tells  us,  he  began  to  hold  his 
nose ;  but  he  still  listened ;  for  there  was  yet 
more  to  be  heard.  From  the  smiles  that  were 
breaking  over  the  lips  of  those  who  read  the  above 
words,  he  gathered  that  they  must  have  overcome 
their  unhappiness.  Yes,  indeed,  they  had.  But 
what  did  they  call  it?  This  was  important — 
even  the  Christian  view  of  unhappiness  seemed 
significant  to  Nietzsche  in  this  inquiry. 

Their  unhappiness,    their  wretchedness,  they 

1  1  Corinthians  i.  20,  21,  26,  27,  28. 

54 


NIETZSCHE  THE  MORALIST 

called  a  trial,  a  gift,  a  distinction !  Not  really  ? 
Yes  indeed  !  As  Nietzsche  points  out :  *  They 
are  wretched,  no  doubt,  all  these  mumblers  and 
underground  forgers,  though  warmly  seated  to 
gether.  But  they  tell  us  their  wretchedness  is  a 
selection  and  distinction  from  God,  that  the  dogs 
which  are  loved  most  are  whipped,  that  their 
misery  may  perhaps  also  be  a  preparation,  a  trial, 
a  schooling ;  perhaps  even  more  —  something 
which  at  some  time  to  come  will  be  requited  and 
paid  back  with  immense  interest  in  gold.  No  ! 
in  happiness.  This  they  call '  blessedness.' l 

At  this  point  Nietzsche  declares  that  he  could 
stand  it  no  longer.  '  Enough,  enough  !  Bad  air  ! 
Bad  air ! '  he  cried.  '  Methinks  this  workshop  of 
virtue  positively  reeks.' 

He  had  now  realised  in  whose  company  he  had 
been  all  this  time. 

nThese  people  who  halted  at  nothing  in  order 
to"  elevate  their  weaknesses  to  the  highest  place 
among  the  virtues,  and  to  monopolise  goodness 
on  earth— who  called  that  good  which  was  tame 
and  soft  and  harmless,  because  they  themselves 
could  only  survive  in  litters  of  cotton  wool ;  who 
coloured  the  earth  with  the  darkness  that  was  in 

1  O.  M.,  1st  Essay,  Aph.  14.  See  also  Epistle  to  the 
Hebrews  xii.  6,  and  Revelation  iii.  19. 

55 


NIETZSCHE 

their  own  bodies ; — who  did  not  scruple  to  dub  all 
manly  and  vital  virtues  odiously  sinful  and  wicked, 
and  who  preferred  to  set  the  life  of  the  whole  world 
at  stake,  rather  than  acknowledge  that  it  was  pre 
cisely  their  own  second-rate,  third-rate,  or  even 
fourth-rate,  vitality  which  was  the  greatest  sin  of 
all ;  who  in  one  and  the  same  breath  preached  their 
utilitarian  '  universal  love '  to  the  powerful,  and 
then  sent  them  to  eternal  damnation  in  another 
world/  Nietzsche  asks,  are  these  people  the  sup 
porters  of  a  noble  or  of  a  slave  morality  ? 

The  answer  is  obvious,  and  we  need  not  labour 
the  point.  But  it  was  so  obvious  to  the  lonely 
hermit,  that  the  thought  of  it  filled  him  with 
horror  and  dread,  and  he  was  moved  to  leave  his 
cell  and  to  descend  into  the  plain,  while  there 
was  yet  time,  with  the  object  of  urging  us  to 
transvalue  our  values. 

In  Christian  values,  Nietzsche  read  nihilism, 
decadence,  degeneration,  and  death.  They  were 
calculated  to  favour  the  multiplication  of  the 
least  desirable  on  earth  :  and,  as  such,  despite  his 
antecedents,  and  with  his  one  desire,  '  the  eleva 
tion  of  the  type  man,'  always  before  him,  he 
condemned  Christian  morality  from  top  to 
bottom.  This  magnificent  attempt  on  the  part 
of  the  low,  the  base,  and  the  worthless,  to  estab- 

56 


NIETZSCHE  THE  MORALIST 

lish  themselves  as  the  most  powerful  on  earth, 
must  be  checked  at  all  costs,  and  with  terrible 
earnestness  he  exhorts  us  to  alter  our  values. 

'  0  my  brethren,  with  whom  lieth  the  greatest 
danger  to  the  whole  human  future?  Is  it  not 
with  the  good  and  the  just  ? 

'  Break  up,  break  up,  I  pray  you,  the  good  and 
the  just ! ' 

This  condemnation  of  Christian  values,  as 
slave  values — which  Nietzsche  regarded  as  his 
greatest  service  to  mankind — he  says  he  would 
write  on  all  walls.  He  tells  us  he  came  just  in 
the  nick  of  time;  to-morrow  might  be  too 
late. 

'  It  is  time  for  man  to  fix  his  goal.  It  is  time 
for  man  to  plant  the  germ  of  his  highest  hope. 

'  His  soil  is  still  rich  enough  for  that  purpose. 
But  that  soil  will  one  day  be  too  poor  and 
exhausted,  and  no  lofty  tree  will  any  longer  be 
able  to  grow  thereon/ l 

1  Z.,  p.  12. 


57 


NIETZSCHE 


CHAPTER   IV 

NIETZSCHE   THE   EVOLUTIONIST 

'  TRANSVALUE  your  yahies  or  parish  i  '  This  was 
the  message  of  the  hermit  Nietzsche  to  the 
people  inhabiting  the  valley  into  which  he  had 
descended.  '  Transvalue  your  values  !  '—that  is 
to  say,  make  them  what  they  once  were,  noble, 
life-approving,  virile!  For  two  thousand  years 
the  roll  of  the  world-wheel  had  been  reversed  — 
Stendhal  had  said  that  many  years  before 
Nietzsche  lived  —  but  it  was  left  to  Nietzsche, 
Stendhal's  admirer  and  pupil,  to  teach  and 
prove  this  fact.  Stendhal,  too,  had  cried  out 
against  the  tameness,  the  lukewarmness,  the 
effeminacy  of  society;  but  Nietzsche  took  up 
this  cry  with  a  voice  more  brazen  than  Stendhal's 
at  a  time  when  mankind  was  in  much  greater 
need  of  it.  Stendhal  had  pointed  enthusiasti 
cally  to  the  sun  and  to  the  passion  of  the  south, 
and  had  donned  a  moral  respirator  whenever  he 

c8 

,V«r 


NIETZSCHE  THE  EVOLUTIONIST 

turned  to  face  the  grey  and  depressing  atmo 
sphere  of  northern  ideas  and  northern  tepidness. 
Nietzsche  follows  his  master's  hint  with  alacrity, 
but  in  doing  so  converts  Stendhal's  clarion  notes 
into  thunder,  and  the  glint  of  Stendhal's  rapier 
into  strokes  of  lightning.1 

When  Nietzsche  began  to  write  Europe  was 
suffering  from  the  worst  kind  of  spiritual  illness 
— weakness  of  will.  Everywhere  comfort  and 
freedom  from  danger  were  becoming  the  highest 
ideals;  everywhere,  too,  virtue  was  being  con 
founded  with  those  qualities  which  led  to  the 
highest  possible  amount  of  security  and  tame, 
back-parlour  pleasures;  and  man  was  gradually 
developing  into  a  harmless  domesticated  type  of 
animal,  capable  of  performing  a  host  of  charm 
ing  little  drawing-room  tricks  which  rejoiced  the 
hearts  of  his  womenfolk. 

Sleep  seemed  to  be  the  greatest  accomplish 
ment.  It  had  become  all  important  to  have  a 
good  night's  rest,  and  everything  was  done  to 
achieve  this  end.  A  man  no  longer  asked  his 
heart  what  it  dictated,  when  he  stood  irresolute 
before  a  daring  deed,  he  simply  consulted  Mor 
pheus,  who  warned  him  that  he  could  not 
promise  him  a  soft  pillow  if  he  did  anything 

i  Q.  E.t  Aplis.  '254,  255,  256. 
59 


NIETZSCHE 

that  was  ever  so  slightly  naughty.  In  the  end, 
Morpheus  would  prevail,  and  thus  all  Europe 
was  beginning  to  snore  peacefully  the  whole 
night  through,  with  marvellous  regularity,  while 
manliness  rotted  and  danger  dwindled.1 

Nietzsche  protested  against  this  state  of  affairs: 
— '  What  is  good  ?  ye  ask.  To  be  brave  is  good. 
Let  the  little  schoolgirls  say :  To  be  good  is  sweet 
and  touching  at  the  same  time.  Ye  say,  a  good 
cause  will  hallow  even  war  ?  I  say  unto  you : 
a  good  war  halloweth  every  cause.  War  and 
courage  have  done  greater  things  than  love ! ' 2 

'  I  pass  through  this  people  and  keep  mine  eyes 
open :  they  have  become  smaller,  and  ever  become 
smaller :  the  reason  thereof  is  their  doctrine  of 
happiness  and  virtue. 

'  For  they  are  moderate  also  in  virtue — because 
they  want  comfort.  With  comfort,  however, 
moderate  virtue  only  is  compatible.  * 

'  Of  man  there  is  little  here :  therefore  do  their 
women  make  themselves  manly.  For  only  he 
who  is  man  enough,  will  save  the  woman  in 
woman. 

'In  their  hearts,  they  want  simply  one  thing 
most  of  all :  that  no  one  hurt  them. 

1  See  Schopenhauer  on  The  Vanity  and  Suffering  of  Life. 
8  Z.t  p.  52. 

60 


NIETZSCHE  THE  EVOLUTIONIST 

'  That,  however,  is  cowardice,  though  it  be 
called  virtue.' l 

Some  there  were,  of  course,  who  were  conscious 
of  the  dreadful  condition  of  things,  and  who 
deplored  it,  without,  however,  being  able  to  put 
their  finger  on  the  root  of  the  evil.  Such  people 
were  most  of  them  pessimists,  and,  at  the  time 
that  Nietzsche  lived,  Schopenhauer  was  their 
leader. 

Sensitive,  noble-minded,  artistic  people,  de 
prived  by  rationalistic  and  atheistic  teachers  of 
the  belief  in  God,  felt  the  ignobleness  of  Euro 
pean  hopes  and  aspirations,  and  knowing  of  no 
better  creed  and  possessing  the  intelligence  to 
see  the  hopelessness  of  things  under  the  rule  of 
the  values  which  then  prevailed,  they  succumbed 
to  a  mood  of  utter  despair,  subscribed  to  Scho 
penhauer's  horror  and  loathing  of  the  world,  and 
regarded  the  very  optimism  of  childhood  with 
suspicion  and  scorn. 

For  a  while  Nietzsche,  too,  was  an  ardent  and 
devoted  follower  of  Schopenhauer.  Godlessness 
was  bad  enough  to  endure:  but  Godlessness  in  a 
world  of  un-pagan  and  effeminate  manhood,  was 
too  much  for  the  loving  student  of  classical  anti 
quity,  and  he  turned  to  Schopenhauer  as  to  one 

1  Z.,  pp.  204,  205,  206. 

61 


NIETZSCHE 

who,  he  thought,  would  understand  how  to  steel 
his  heart  against  life's  misery. 

But  this  opiate  did  not  maintain  its  sway  over 
Nietzsche  long.  Our  poet  was  of  a  type  too 
courageous  and  too  vigorous  to  be  able  to 
surrender  himself  so  completely  to  sorrow  and 
to  Buddhistic  consolations.  Gradually  he  began 
to  regard  the  humble  and  resigned  attitude  of 
the  pessimist  before  life's  hardships  and  modern 
ity's  greyness  as  unworthy  of  a  spirited  and 
active  man.  Slowly  it  dawned  upon  him  that 
the  root  of  the  evil  lay,  not  in  the  constitution  of 
the  earth,  but  in  man  himself,  and  in  man's 
actual  values.  If  man  could  be  roused  to  pursue 
higher  ideals ;  if  he  could  be  moved  to  kill  the 
poisonous  snake  of  ignoble  values  that  had 
crawled  into  his  throat  and  choked  him  while  he 
was  in  slumber ; 1  in  fact,  if  man  could  surpass 
himself  and  regard  the  reversal  of  the  world's 
engines,  for  the  last  two  thousand  years,  as 
Stendhal  had  done — that  is  to  say,  as  the 
grossest  error  and  most  ridiculous  faux  pas  that 
had  ever  been  made — then,  Nietzsche  thought, 
pessimism  and  Schopenhauer  might  go  to  the 
deuce,  and  conscious,  sensitive,  intellectual,  and 
artistic  Europe  would  once  more  be  able  to  smile 
1  Z.,  pp.  192,  193. 

62 


NIETZSCHE  THE  EVOLUTIONIST 

instead  of  shuddering  at  the  thought  of  mankind's 
former  qualities. 

Thus  it  was  the  condemnation  of  modern 
values,  together  with  the  thought  of  man's  being 
able  to  surpass  himself,  which  gave  Nietzsche 
the  grounds  and  the  necessary  strength  for 
abandoning  pessimism  and  embracing  that  wise 
optimism  which  characterises  the  whole  of  his 
works  after  The  Joyful  Wisdom. 

True,  God  was  dead;  but  that  ought  only  to 
make  man  feel  more  self-reliant,  more  creative, 
prouder.  Undoubtedly  God  was  dead :  but  man 
could  now  hold  himself  responsible  for  himself. 
He  could  now  seek  a  goal  in  manhood,  on  earth, 
and  one  that  was  at  least  within  the  compass  of 
his  powers.  Long  enough  had  he  squinted 
heavenwards,  with  the  result  that  he  had 
neglected  his  task  on  earth.1 

'  Dead  are  all  Gods ! '  Nietzsche  cries, '  now  we 
will  that  Superman  live ! ' 2 

We  are  now  before  Nietzsche  the  evolutionist, 
and  we  must  define  him,  relatively  to  those  other 
evolutionists  with  whom  we,  as  English  people, 
are  already  familiar. 

To  begin  with,  then,  let  us  dispose  of  the 
fundamental  question  :  Nietzsche's  concept  of  life. 

1  See  Z.,  p.  98  tt  seq.  2  Z.,  p.  91. 

63 


NIETZSCHE 

We  have  had  life  variously  defined  for  us  by  our 
own  writers,  and  perhaps  one  among  Nietzsche's 
greatest  contemporaries  in  England — Herbert 
Spencer — defined  it  in  the  most  characteristically 
English  fashion.  Spencer  said :  '  Life  is  activity/ 
or  '  the  continuous  adjustment  of  internal  relations 
to  external  relations/  Now  there  is  absolutely 
nothing  in  either  of  these  definitions,  no  sugges 
tion  or  hint,  which  would  lead  the  most  suspicious 
to  conjecture  what  life  really  is.  'Activity' 
reveals  nothing  of  life's  passions,  its  hate,  its 
envy,  its  covetousness,  its  hard,  inexorable  prin 
ciples;  the  process  of  the  continual  adjustments 
of  internal  relations  to  external  relations  might 
mean  the  serpent's  digestion  of  its  prey,  or  the 
training  of  an  opera  singer's  voice,  and  it  might 
also  be  a  scientific  formula  for  a  'moral  order 
of  things.'.  Both  definitions  are  delightfully 
unheroic  and  vague ;  though  they  do  not  com 
promise  the  writer  they  compromise  with  every 
thing  else,  and  to  start  out  with  them  is  to 
shelve  the  question  in  a  way  which  allows  of  our 
subsequently  weaving  all  the  romance  and  sweet 
ness  possible  into  life,  and  of  making  it  as 
pretty  as  a  little  nursery  story. 

Nietzsche,   always   eager   for  a   practical    and 
tangible  idea,  naturally  could  not  accept  these 


NIETZSCHE  THE  EVOLUTIONIST 

two  definitions  as  expressing  anything  profound 
about  life  at  all.  Looking  into  the  face  of  nature, 
and  reading  her  history  from  the  amoeba  with  its 
predatory  pseudo-podia,  to  the  lion  with  its 
murderous  prehensile  claws,  he  defined  life 
practically,  uprightly,  and  bravely,  as  *  appropria 
tion,  injury,  conquest  of  the  strange  and  weak, 
suppression,  severity,  obtrusion  of  its  own  forms, 
incorporation,  and,  at  least,  putting  it  mildest, 
exploitation.' l 

Thus,  as  we  see,  from  the  start  Nietzsche 
closes  his  eyes  at  nothing,  he  does  not  want  life  to 
be  a  pretty  tale  if  it  is  not  one.  He  wants  to 
know  it  as  it  is :  for  he  is  convinced  that  this  is 
the  only  way  of  arriving  at  sound  principles  as  to 
the  manner  in  which  human  existence  should  be 
led. 

'  Appropriation/  then,  he  takes  as  a  fact :  he 
does  not  argue  it  away,  any  more  than  he  tries  to 
argue  away  'injury,' '  conquest  of  the  strange  and 
weak/  '  suppression/  and  '  incorporation.'  These 
things  are  only  too  apparent,  and  he  states  them 
bravely  in  his  definition.  We  know  life  is  all 
this ;  but  how  much  more  comfortable  it  is,  when 
we  are  sitting  in  our  soft  easy-chairs  before  our 
cheerful  fires,  to  think  that  life  is  merely  activity ! 

1  O.  E.y  p.  226. 
a  65 


NIETZSCHE 

To  believe  that  there  is  a  moral  order  in  the 
universe  is  to  believe  that  these  unpleasant 
things  in  Nietzsche's  definition  will  one  day  be 
overcome.  This  was  the  position  Christianity 
assumed  from  the  start.  But,  though  it  was 
excusable  in  a  religion  fighting  for  power,  and 
compelled  to  use  nice  and  attractive  words  for  its 
followers,  to  suppose  that  all  the  misery  on  earth 
will  one  day  be  transformed  by  God's  wisdom  into 
perfect  bliss ;  such  an  attitude  is  quite  unpardon 
able  in  the  case  of  a  philosopher  or  even  of  a  poet. 
When  Browning  chanted  smugly :  '  God 's  in  His 
heaven  :  All 's  right  with  the  world,'  he  confessed 
himself  a  mediocre  spirit  with  one  stroke  of  the 
pen.  And  when  Spencer  wrote  that  the  blind 
process  of  evolution  '  must  inevitably  favour  all 
changes  of  nature  which  increase  life  and  augment 
happiness,'  he  did  the  same.  We  may  now  per 
haps  understand  Nietzsche's  impatience  of  his 
predecessors  and  contemporaries,  who  refused  to 
see  precisely  what  he  saw  in  the  face  of  nature. 

But  even  in  his  extended  definition  of  life,  the 
modern  biologist  brings  himself  no  nearer  to 
Nietzsche's  honest  standpoint,  and  for  the  follow 
ing  reasons : — 

The  modern  biologist  says,  this  '  activity '  he 
speaks  of  has  a  precise  meaning.  It  connotes 
66 


NIETZSCHE  THE  EVOLUTIONIST 

'  the  struggle  for  existence/  or  in  other  words : 
'self-defence/  (Again  he  is  looking  at  life 
through  moral  or  Christian  glasses;  because  if 
everything  on  earth  is  done  in  self-defence,  even 
the  devil  himself  is  argued  out  of  existence,  and 
God  remains  creator  of  the  '  good '  alone.) 
Nietzsche  replies  by  denying  this  flatly.  He 
says  that  the  definition  is  again  inadequate.  He 
warns  us  not  to  confound  Malthus  with  nature.1 
He  admits  that  the  struggle  occurs,  but  only  as 
an  exception.  '  The  general  aspect  of  life  is  not 
a  state  of  want  or  hunger ;  it  is  rather  a  state  of 
opulence,  luxuriance,  and  even  absurd  prodigality 
— where  there  is  a  struggle,  it  is  a  struggle  for 
power.'  —Will  to  power  and  not  will  to  live  is 
motivgJbrCG^Qf  Hfe. 

'  Wherever  I  found  living  matter/  he  says, '  I 
found  will  to  power,  and  even  in  the  servant  I 
found  the  yearning  to  be  master. 

'  Only  where  there  is  life,  there  is  will :  though 
not  will  to  live,  but  thus  I  teach  thee — WILL  TO 
POWER.'  2 

Is  there  no  aggression  without  the  struggle  for 
existence  ?  Is  there  no  voluptuousness  in  a 
position  of  power  for  its  own  sake  ?  Of  course 

1  Twilight  of  the  Idoh,  Part  9,  Aph.  14. 

2  Z.,  pp.  136,  137. 

67 


NIETZSCHE 

there  is !  And  one  wonders  how  these  English 
biologists  could  ever  have  been  schoolboys  with 
out  noticing  these  facts.  As  Nietzsche  points  out, 
however,  they  are  every  one  of  them  labouring 
under  the  Christian  ideal  still — in  spite  of  all  their 
upsetting  of  the  first  chapter  of  Genesis,  and  in 
spite  of  all  their  blasting  of  the  miracles.  But, 
if  life  is  the  supreme  aim  of  all,  how  is  it  that 
many  things  are  valued  higher  than  life  by  living 
beings  ?  If  the  will  to  live  sometimes  finds  itself 
overpowered  by  another  will — more  particularly 
in  great  warriors,  great  prophets,  great  artists, 
and  great  heroes — what  is  this  mightier  force 
which  thus  overpowers  it  ?  We  have  heard  what 
Nietzsche  calls  it — it  is  the  Will  to  Power. 

'  Psychologists  should  bethink  themselves 
before  putting  down  the  instinct  of  self-preserva 
tion  as  the  cardinal  instinct  of  an  organic  being. 
A  living  thing  seeks  above  all  to  discharge 
its  strength — life  itself  is  Will  to  Power;  self- 
preservation  is  only  one  of  the  indirect  and  most 
frequent  results  thereof.' l 

In  spite  of  everything  we  have  already  said, 

Nietzsche's  disagreement  with  our  own  biologists 

may  still  seem  to  many  but  a  play  upon  words. 

A  moment's  meditation,  however — more  particu- 

1  G.  E.y  p.  20. 

68 


NIETZSCHE  THE  EVOLUTIONIST 

larly  over  the  passage  just  quoted — will  show 
that  it  is  really  much  deeper  than  this.  It  is  one 
thing  to  regard  an  animal  as  a  mere  automaton, 
prowling  around  to  satisfy  its  hunger,  and  happy  to 
remain  inactive  when  the  sensation  of  hunger  is 
appeased,  and  quite  another  to  regard  an  animal 
as  a  battery  of  accumulated  forces  which  must 
be  discharged  at  all  costs  (and  for  good  or  evil), 
with  only  temporary  lapses  of  purely  self- 
preservative  desires  and  self-preservative  actions. 
All  the  different  consequences  of  these  two  views 
will  occur  to  the  thinker  in  an  instant. 

Upon  this  basis,  then,  the  Will  to  Power, 
Nietzsche  builds  up  a  cosmogony  which  also 
assumes  that  species  have  been  evolved;  but 
again,  in  the  processes  of  that  evolution  he  is  at 
variance  with  Darwin  and  all  the  natural- 
selectionists. 

Nietzsche  cannot  be  persuaded  that  'mechanical 
adjustment  to  ambient  conditions,'  or  '  adaptation 
to  environment ' — both  purely  passive,  meek,  and 
uncreative  functions — should  be  given  the  im 
portance,  as  determining  factors,  which  the 
English  and  German  schools  give  them.  With 
Samuel  Butler,  he  protests  against  this  'pitch 
forking  of  mind  and  spirit  out  of  the  universe,' 
and  points  imperatively  to  an  inner  creative  will 

69 


NIETZSCHE 

in  living  organisms,  which  ultimately  makes 
environment  and  natural  conditions  subservient 
and  subject.  In  the  Genealogy  of  Morals l  he 
makes  it  quite  clear  that  he  would  ascribe  the 
greatest  importance  to  a  power  in  the  organism 
itself,  to  '  the  highest  functionaries  in  the  animal 
in  which  the  life-will  appears  as  an  active  and 
formative  principle/  and  that  even  in  the  matter 
of  the  mysterious  occurrence  of  varieties  (sports) 
he  would  seek  for  inner  causes.  Darwin  himself 
threw  out  only  a  hint  in  this  direction ;  that  is 
why  it  is  safe  to  suppose  that,  if  Nietzsche  and 
Darwin  are  ever  reconciled,  it  will  probably  be 
precisely  on  this  ground.  In  the  Origin  of 
Species,  speaking  of  the  causes  of  variability, 
Darwin  said  :  * .  .  .  There  are  two  factors,  namely 
the  nature  of  the  organism,  and  the  nature  of  the 
conditions.  The  former  seem  to  be  much  the 
more  important?  for  nearly  similar  variations 
sometimes  arise  under,  as  far  as  we  can  judge, 
dissimilar  conditions ;  and  on  the  other  hand, 
dissimilar  variations  arise  under  conditions  which 
appear  to  be  uniform.' 

Thus  differing  widely  from  the  orthodox  school 
of  evolutionists,  Nietzsche  nevertheless  believed 

1  Second  Essay,  Aph.  12. 

2  The  italics  are  mine. — A.  M.  L. 

70 


NIETZSCHE  THE  EVOLUTIONIST 

their  hypothesis  to  be  sound ;  but  once  more  he 
has  an  objection  to  raise.  Why  did  they  halt 
where  they  halted  ? 

If  the  process  is  a  fact,  if  things  have  become 
what  they  are,  and  have  not  always  been  so ;  then 
why  should  we  rest  on  our  oars  ?  If  it  was 
possible  for  man  to  struggle  up  from  barbarism, 
and  still  more  remotely  from  the  lower  Primates, 
and  reach  the  zenith  of  his  physical  development ; 
why,  Nietzsche  asks,  should  he  not  surpass 
himself  and  attain  to  Superman  by  evolving  in 
the  same  degree  volitionally  and  mentally  ? 

'  The  most  careful  ask  to-day :  "  How  is  man 
preserved  ? "  But  Zarathustra  asketh  as  the  only 
and  first  one  :  "  How  is  man  surpassed  ? " l 

'  All  beings  (in  your  genealogical  ladder)  have 
created  something  beyond  themselves,  and  are  ye 
going  to  be  the  ebb  of  this  great  tide  ? 

'  Behold  I  teach  you  Superman ! ' 2 

And  now,  again,  at  the  risk  of  being  mono 
tonous,  I  must  point  to  yet  another  difference 
between  Nietzsche  and  the  prevailing  school  of 
evolutionists.  Whereas  the  latter,  in  their 
unscrupulous  optimism,  believed  that  out  of  the 
chaotic  play  of  blind  forces  something  highly 
desirable  and  '  good  '  would  ultimately  be  evolved; 
1  z.,  p.  351.  2  z.,  p.  6. 


NIETZSCHE 

whereas  they  tacitly,  though  not  avowedly,  be 
lieved  that  their  'fittest'  in  the  struggle  for 
existence  would  eventually  prove  to  be  the  best — 
in  fact  that  we  should  '  muddle  through  '  to  per 
fection  somehow,  and  that  something  really  noble 
and  important  would  be  sure  to  result  from  John 
Brown's  contest  with  Harry  Smith  for  the  highest 
place  in  an  insurance  office,  for  instance ; 
Nietzsche  disbelieved  from  the  bottom  of  his 
heart  in  this  chance  play  of  blind  and  meaning 
less  tendencies.  He  said :  Given  a  degenerate, 
mean,  and  base  environment  and  the  fittest  to 
survive  therein  will  be  the  man  who  is  best 
adapted  to  degeneracy,  meanness,  and  baseness — 
therefore  the  worst  kind  of  man.  Given  a  com 
munity  of  parasites,  and  it  may  be  that  the 
flattest,  the  slimiest,  and  the  softest,  will  be  the 
fittest  to  survive.  Such  faith  in  blind  forces 
Nietzsche  regarded  merely  as  the  survival  of  the 
old  Christian  belief  in  the  moral  order  of  things, 
togged  out  in  scientific  apparel  to  suit  modern 
tastes.  He  saw  plainly,  that  if  man  were  to  be 
elevated  at  all,  no  blind  struggle  in  his  present 
conditions  would  ever  effect  that  end ;  for  the 
';  present  conditions  themselves  make  those  the 
]  fittest  to  survive  in  them  who  are  persons  of 
/  absolutely  undesirable  gifts  and  propensities. 

72 


NIETZSCHE  THE  EVOLUTIONIST 

He  declared  (and  here  we  are  in  the  very  heart 
of  Nietzscheism)  that  nothing  but  a  total  change 
in  these  conditions,  a  complete  transvaluation  of 
all  values,  would  ever  alter  man  and  make  him 
more  worthy  of  his  past.  For  it  is  values,  values, 
and  again  values,  that  mould  men,  and  rear  men, 
and  create  men ;  and  ignoble  values  make  ignoble 
men,  and  noble  values  make  noble  men !  Thus 
it  was  in  the  beginning,  is  now,  and  ever  shall  be, 
truth  without  end — for  men, 

Nietzsche  realised  '  all  that  could  still  be  made 
out  of  man,  through  a  favourable  accumulation 
and  augmentation  of  human  powers  and  arrange 
ments  ' ;  he  knew  '  how  unexhausted  man  still  is 
for  the  greatest  possibilities,  and  how  often  in 
the  past  the  type  man  has  stood  in  mysterious 
and  dangerous  crossways,  and  has  launched  forth 
upon  the  right  or  the  wrong  road,  impelled 
merely  by  a  whim,  or  by  a  hint  from  the  giant 
Chance.'1  And  now,  he  was  determined  that 
whether  man  wished  to  listen  or  not,  at  least 
he  should  be  told  of  the  ultimate  disaster  that 
awaited  him,  if  he  continued  in  his  present 
direction.  For,  there  was  yet  time  ! 

It  is    to    higher   men    that    Nietzsche   really 
makes  his  appeal,  the  leaders  and  misleaders  of 
1  o.  E.,  P.  130. 
73 


NIETZSCHE 

the  mob.  He  had  no  concern  with  the  multitude 
and  they  did  not  need  him.  The  world  had  seen 
philosophies  enough  which  had  advocated  the 
cause  of  the  '  greatest  number ' — English  libraries 
were  stacked  with  such  works.  What  was  re 
quired  was,  to  convert  those  rare  men  who  give 
the  direction— the  heads  of  the  various  throngs — 
the  vanguard. 

'  Awake  and  listen,  ye  lonely  ones !  From  the 
future,  winds  are  coming  with  a  gentle  beating 
of  wings,  and  there  cometh  good  tidings  for 
fine  ears. 

^  Ye  lonely  ones  of  to-day,  ye  who  stand  apart, 
ye  shall  one  day  be  a  people :  from  you,  who  have 
chosen  yourselves,  a  chosen  people  shall  arise 
and  from  it  Superman.' l 

1  Z.,.  89. 


74 


NIETZSCHE  THE  SOCIOLOGIST 


CHAPTER  V 

NIETZSCHE   THE   SOCIOLOGIST 

FOR  Nietzsche,  as  we  are  beginning  to  see,  a 
fitting  title  is  hard  to  find.  Unless  we  coin  new 
names  for  things  that  have  not  yet  been  given 
names,  Nietzsche  remains  without  a  title  among 
his  fellow  thinkers.  He  has  been  called  the 
'arch-anarchist/  which  he  is  not;  he  has  been 
called  the  'preacher  of  brutality/  which  he  is 
not ;  he  has  been  called  the  '  egoist/  which  he  is 
not.  But  all  these  titles  were  conferred  upon 
him  by  people  whose  interest  it  was  to  reduce 
him  in  the  public's  esteem.  If  he  must  be 
named,  however,  and  we  suppose  he  must,  the 
best  title  would  obviously  be  that  which  would 
distinguish  him  most  exactly  from  his  colleagues. 
Now,  how  does  Nietzsche  stand  out  from  the 
ranks  of  almost  all  other  philosophers  ?  By  the 
fact  that  he  was  throughout  his  life  an  '  Advocate 
of  Higher  Man.'  Whereas  other  philosophers 
75 


NIETZSCHE 

and  scholars  had  always  thought  they  had  some 
divine  message  to  impart  in  the  cause  of  the 
'  greatest  number ' ;  Nietzsche — the  typical  miner 
and  underminer — believed  that  his  mission  was 
to  stand  for  a  neglected  minority,  for  higher  men, 
for  the  gold  in  the  mass  of  quartz. 

No  title  therefore  could  be  more  fair,  and  at 
the  same  time  more  essentially  descriptive,  than 
the  '  Advocate  of  Higher  Man/  and  in  giving  this 
title  to  Nietzsche,  we  immediately  outline  him 
against  that  assembly  of  his  colleagues  who  were 
'  Advocates  of  the  Greatest  Number.' 

It  is  of  the  first  importance  to  humanity  that 
its  higher  individuals  should  be  allowed  to  attain 
their  full  development,  for  only  by  means  of  its 
heroes  can  the  human  race  be  led  forward  step 
by  step  to  higher  and  ever  higher  levels.  In 
view  of  the  fact  that  Nietzsche  realised  this,  some 
of  his  principles,  when  given  general  application, 
may  very  naturally  appear  to  be  both  iniquitous 
and  subversive,  and  those  who  read  him  with  the 
idea  that  he  is  preaching  a  gospel  for  all  are 
perfectly  justified  if  they  turn  away  in  horror 
from  his  works.  The  mistake  they  make,  how 
ever,  is  to  suppose  that  he,  like  most  other 
philosophers  with  whom  they  are  familiar,  is  an 
advocate  of  the  greatest  number. 


NIETZSCHE  THE  SOCIOLOGIST 

Let  us  take  a  single  instance.  In  The  Honey 
Sacrifice1  the  phrase  'Become  what  thou  art,' 
occurs.  Now  it  is  obvious  that  however  legiti 
mate  this  command  may  be  when  applied  to  the 
highest  and  best,  it  becomes  dangerous  and 
seditious  when  applied  to  each  individual  of  the 
mass  of  mankind.  And  this  explains  the  number 
of  errors  that  are  rife  concerning  Nietzsche's 
gospel.  Whenever  Nietzsche  spoke  esoterically, 
his  enemies  declared  that  he  was  pronouncing 
maxims  for  the  greatest  number;  whenever  he 
spoke  for  the  greatest  number,  as  he  does  again 
and  again  in  his  allusions  to  the  mediocre,  he 
was  accused  of  speaking  esoterically.  How  would 
any  other  philosophy  have  fared  under  such 
misrepresentation  and  calumny  ? 

Nietzsche  couHiiot4^1ie¥e-m--eqmlityf  for witk- 
ilLhim,  justice  '  Those 

to  whom  it  gives  pleasure  to  think  that  men  are 
equal,  he  conjures  not  to  confound  pleasure  with 
truth,  and,  like  Professor  Huxley,  he  finds  himself 
obliged  to  recognise  'the  natural  inequality  of 
men.' 

But,  far  from  deploring  this  fact,  he  would 
fain  have  accentuated  and  intensified  it.  This 
inequality,  to  Nietzsche,  is  a  condition  to  be 

1  Z.,  chap.  Ixi. 

77 


NIETZSCHE 

exploited  and  to  be  made  use  of  by  the  legislator. 
The  higher  men  of  a  society  in  which  gradations 
of  rank  are  recognised  as  a  natural  and  desirable 
condition  constitute  the  class  in  which  the  hopes 
of  a  real  elevation  of  humanity  may  be  placed. 
The  Divine  Manu,  Laotse,  Confucius,  Muhammad, 
Jesus  Christ — all  these  men,  who  in  their  sublime 
arrogance  actually  converted  man  into  a  mirror 
in  which  they  saw  themselves  and  their  doctrines 
reflected,  and  who  in  thus  converting  man  into 
a  mirror  really  made  him  feel  happy  in  the 
function  of  reflecting  alone : — these  leaders  are  the 
types  Nietzsche  refers  to  when  he  speaks  of  higher 
men. 

Ruling,  like  all  other  functions  which  require 
the  great  to  justify  them,  has  fallen  into  dis 
repute,  thanks  to  the  incompetent  amateurs  that 
have  tried  their  hand  at  the  game.  As  in  the 
Fine  Arts,  so  in  leading  and  ruling;  it  is  the 
dilettantes  that  have  broken  our  faith  in  human 
performances.  The  really  great  ruler  reaches 
hjsKftT^  an  epoch,  a  party,  a 

nation  or  the  world,  to  the  best  advantage  of 
each  of  these;  but  it  does  not  follow  that  the 
motive  power  propelling  him  should  necessarily 
be  the  conscious  pursuit  of  the  best  advantage 
of  those  he  rules, — this  is  merely  a  fortuitous 

78 


NIETZSCHE  THE  SOCIOLOGIST 

circumstance  curiously  associated  with  greatness 
in  ruling,  —  generally  speaking,  however,  his  only 
conscious  motive  is  the  gratification  of  his  in 
ordinate  will  to  power. 

~~The  innocent  fallacy  of  democracy  lies  in 
supposing  that  by  a  mere  search,  by  a  mere 
rummaging  and  fumbling  among  a  motley  popu 
lace,  one  man  or  several  men  can  be  found, 
who  are  able  to  take  the  place  of  the  rare  and 
ideal  ruler.  As  if  the  mere  fact  of  searching  and 
rummaging  were  not  in  itself  a  confession  of 
failure,  —  a  confession  that  this  man  does  not 
exist  !  For  if  he  existed  he  would  have  asserted 
himself!  He  would  have  needed  no  democratic 
exploration  party  to  unearth  him. 

'  There  is  no  sorer  misfortune  in  all  human 
destiny,  than  when  the  powerful  of  the  earth 
are  not  at  the  same  time  the  first  men.  Then 
everything  becometh  false  and  warped  and 
monstrous.'  1 

'For,  my  brethren,  the  best  shall  rule:  the 
best  will  rule  !  And  where  the  teaching  is 
different,  there  —  the  best  is  lacking.'  2^~ 

Here  we  observe  that  Nietzsche  advocated  an 
aristocratic  arrangement  of  society.  A  firm 
believer  in  tradition,  law,  and  order,  and,  in  spite 

1  £.,  p.  299.  2  Z.,  pp.  256,  257. 

79 


V\i 

4vu<r  Jit* 


NIETZSCHE 

of  his  opponents'  accusations,  an  undaunted 
enemy  of  Anarchy  and  laisser- alter,  he  saw  in 
Socialism  and  Democracy  nothing  more  than 
two  slave  organisations  for  the  raising  of  every 
individual  to  his  highest  power.  Individuality 
made  as  general  as  possible ;  or,  in  other  words, 
Socialism  and  Democracy  meant  to  Nietzsche 
the  annihilation  of  all  higher  aims  and  hopes. 
It  meant  valuing  all  the  weeds  and  noble  plants 
alike,  and  with  such  a  valuation  the  noble  plants, 
TTemg  in  the  minority,  must  necessarily  suffer 
and  ultimately  die  out^  Where  everybody  is 
somebody,  nobody  is  anybody.  Socialism,  i.e. 
organised  Individualism,  seemed  to  Nietzsche 
merely  the  reflection  in  politics  of  the  Christian 
principle  that  all  men  are  alike  before  God. 
Grant  immortality  to  every  Tom,  Dick,  and 
Harry,  and,  in  the  end,  every  Tom,  Dick,  or 
Harry  will  believe  in  equal  rights  before  he  can 
even  hope  to  reach  Heaven.  But  to  deny  the 
privileges  of  rare  men  implies  the  proscription 
from  life  of  all  high  trees  with  broad  branches, — 
those  broad  branches  that  protect  the  herd  from 
the  rain,  but  which  also  keep  the  sun  from  the 
envious  and  ambitious  shrub, — and  thus  it  would 
mean  that  the  world  would  gradually  assume  the 
appearance  of  those  vast  Scotch  moors  of  gorse 

80 


NIETZSCHE  THE  SOCIOLOGIST 

and  heather,  where  liberalism  and  mediocrity 
are  rampant,  but  where  all  loftiness  is 
dead. 

Nietzsche  was  a  profound  believer  in  the  value 
of  tradition,  in  the  value  of  general  discipline 
lasting  over  long  periods.  He  knew  that  all 
that  is  great  and  lasting  and  intensely  moving 
has  been  the  result  of  the  law  of  castes  or  of 
the  laws  governing  the  individual  members  of 
a  caste  throughout  many  generations.1  This 
building  up  of  the  rare  man,  of  the  great  man 
Tof  tfre  ffljjjvfttod  type  in  a  Darwinian  sense)  as 
every  scientist  is  aware,  is  utterly  frustrated  by 
anything  in  the  way  of  injudicious  and  careless 
cross-breeding  (see  Darwin  on  the  degeneration 
of  the  cultivated  types  of  animals  through  the 
action  of  promiscuous  breeding),  by  democratic 
mesalliances  of  all  kinds,  and  by  the  laisser  alter 
which  is  one  of  the  worst  evils  of  that  kind  of 
freedom  which  tends  to  prevail  when  the  slaves 
of  a  community  have  succeeded  in  asserting  and 
expressing  their  insignificant  and  miserable  little 
individualities. 

Believing  all  this,  Nietzsche  could  not  help  but 
Advocate  the  rearing  of  a  select  and  aristocratic 
caste,  and  in  none  of  his  exhortations  is  he  more 

1  O.  E.,  Aph.  188. 
F  8l 


NIETZSCHE 

sincere  than  when  he  appeals  to  higher  men  to 
sow  the  seeds  of  a  nobility  for  the  future. 

'  0  my  brethren,  I  consecrate  you  to  be,  and 
show  unto  you  the  way  unto  a  new  nobility.  Ye 
shall  become  procreators  and  breeders  and  sowers 
of  the  future. 

'  Verily,  ye  shall  not  become  a  nobility  one  might 
buy,  like  shopkeepers  with  shopkeepers'  gold. 
For  all  that  hath  its  fixed  price  is  of  little  worth. 

'  Not  whence  ye  come  be  your  honour  in 
future,  but  whither  ye  go !  Your  will,  and  your 
foot  that  longeth  to  get  beyond  yourselves, — be 
that  your  new  honour  ! '  «.-»«-  ' ; 

'Your  children's  land  ye  shall  love  (be  this 
your  new  nobility),  the  land  undiscovered  in  the 
remotest  sea!  For  it  I  bid  you  set  sail  and 
seek ! ' l 

s  'Every  elevation  of  the  type  man,'  says 
Nietzsche,  'has  hitherto  been  the  work  of  an 
aristocratic  society — and  so  will  it  always  be — a 
society  believing  in  a  long  scale  of  gradations  of 
rank  and  differences  of  worth  among  human 
beings,  and  requiring  slavery  in  some  form  or 
other.  Without  the  £>a#/ios  of  distance,  such  as 
grows  out  of  the  incarnated  differences  of  classes, 
ojit  of  the  constant  outlooking  and  downlooking 


NIETZSCHE  THE  SOCIOLOGIST 

of  the  ruling  caste  on  subordinates  and  instru 
ments,  and  out  of  their  equally  constant  practice 
of  obeying  and  commanding,  of  keeping  down  and 
keeping  at  a  distance — that  other  more  mysterious 
pathos  could  never  have  arisen,  the  longing  for  an 
ever  new  widening  distance  within  the  soul  itself, 
the  formation  of  ever  higher,  rarer,  further,  more 
extended,  more  comprehensive  states,  in  short, 
just  the  elevation  of  the  type  '  man/  the  con 
tinued  '  self-surmounting  of  man/  to  use  a  moral 
formula  in  a  super-moral  sense/ l^ 

I  cannot  attempt  to  giveji  full  account  of  the 
society  Nic^che L  would  fain  have  seen  established 
on  earth.  It  will  be  found  exhaustively  described 
in  Aph.  57  of  the  Antichrist :  while  in  the  book  of 
Manu  (Max  Muller's  '  Sacred  Books  of  the  East/ 
No.  25),  similar  sociological  prescriptions  are  to  be 
found,  correlated  with  all  the  imposing  machinery 
of  divine  revelation,  supernatural  authority,  and 
religious  earnestness. 

Briefly,  Nietzsche  says  this  : — 

It  is  ridiculous  to  pretend  to  treat  every  one 

without    regard    to    those    natural    distinctions 

which  are  manifested  by  superior  intellectuality, 

or  exceptional  muscular  strength,  or  mediocrity 

of  spiritual  and  bodily  powers,  or  inferiority  of 

1  O.  E.t  p.  223. 

83 


NIETZSCHE 

both.  He  tells  us  that  it  is  not  the  legislator, 
but  nature  hersejj,  who  establishes  these  broad 
classes,  and  to  ignore  them  when  forming  a 
society  would  be  just  as  foolish  as  to  ignore  the 
order  of  rank  among  materials  and  structural 
principles  when  building  a  monument.  Though 
the  base  of  a  pyramid  does  not  require  to  be  of 
the  very  finest  marble,  we  know  it  must  be  both 
broad  and  massive.  Nietzsche  declares  that  no 
society  has  any  solidarity  wbich^is^  not  founded 
uporL  a  broad  basis  of  mediocrity.  Though  the 
stones  get  fewer  in  the  layers  as  we  ascend  to  the 
top  of  the  pyramid,  we  know  that  their  grada 
tion  is  necessary  if  the  highest  point  is  to  be 
reached.  Nietzsche  believes  in  the  long  scale 
of  gradations  of  rank  with  the  ascending  line 
leading  always  to  the  highest — even  if  he  be  only 
a  single  individual.  Though  the  very  uppermost 
point  consists  of  a  single  stone,  it  is  around  that 
single  stone  that  the  weather  will  rage  most 
furiously  and  the  sun  shine  most  gorgeously. 
That  single  stone  will  be  the  first  to  cleave  the 
heavy  shower,  and  the  first,  too,  to  meet  the 
lightning.  Nietzsche  says :  'Life  always  becomes 
harder  towards  the  summit, — the  cold  increases, 
responsibility  increases.' l 

1  Antichrist,  Aph.  57. 

84 


NIETZSCHE  THE  SOCIOLOGIST 

*  Saepius  ventis  agitatur  ingens 
pinus,  et  celsae  graviore  casu 
decidunt  turres,  feriuntque  summos 

fulgura  monies.'1— HORACE,  Carm.  n.  x. 

Thus  he  would  have  the  intellectually  superior, 
those  who  can  bear  responsibility  and  endure  hard 
ships,  at  the  head.  Beneath  them  are  the  warriors, 
the  physically  strong,  who  are  '  the  guardians  of 
right,  the  keepers  of  order  and  security,  the  king 
above  all  as  the  highest  formula  of  warrior,  judge, 
and  keeper  of  the  law.  The  second  in  rank  are 
the  executive  of  the  most  intellectual.'  And 
below  this  caste  are  the  mediocre.  '  Handicraft, 
trade,  agriculture,  science,  the  greater  part  of  art, 
in  a  word,  the  whole  compass  of  business  activity, 
is  exclusively  compatible  with  an  average  amount 
of  ability  and  pretension.'  At  the  very  base  of 
the  social  edifice,  Nietzsche  sees  the  class  of  man 
who  thrives  best  when  he  is  well  looked  after  and 
closely  observed, — the  man  who  is  happy  to 
serve,  not  because  he  must,  but  because  he  is 
what  he  is, — the  man  uncorrupted  by  political 
and  religious  lies  concerning  equality,  liberty,  and 
fraternity, — who  is  half  conscious  of  the  abyss 
which  separates  him  from  his  superiors,  and  who 

1  '  The  big  pine  is  more  often  shaken  by  the  winds :  the 
higher  a  tower,  the  heavier  is  the  fall  thereof,  and  it  is  th« 
tops  of  the  mountains  that  the  lightning  strikes.' 

85 


NIETZSCHE 

is  happiest  when  performing  those  acts  which  are 
not  beyond  his  limitations. 

He  forestalls  this  sketch  of  his  ideal  society  by 
enunciating  the  moral  code  wherewith  he  would 
transvalue  our  present  values,  and  I  shall  now 
give  this  code  without  a  single  remark  or  com 
ment,  feeling  quite  sure  that  the  reader  who  has 
understood  Nietzsche  so  far  will  not  require  any 
assistance  in  seeing  that  it  is  the  necessary  and 
logical  outcome  of  the  rest  of  his  teaching. 

'  What  is  good  ?  All  that  increases  the  feeling 
of  power,  will  to  power,  power  itself  in  man. 

'  What  is  bad  ? — All  that  proceeds  from  weak 
ness. 

'  What  is  happiness  ? — The  feeling  that  power 
increases,  that  resistance  is  overcome. 

'  Not  contentedness,  but  more  power ;  not  peace 
at  any  price,  but  warfare ;  not  virtue,  but  capacity 
(virtue  in  the  Renaissance  style,  virtu  free  from 
any  moralic  acid).j 

I  cannot  well  close  this  chapter  on  Nietzsche's 
sociological  views  without  touching  upon  two  of 
the  most  important  elements  in  modern  society, 
arid  his  treatment  of  them.  I  refer  to  '  altruism ' 

1  Antichrist,  Aph.  2. 

86 


NIETZSCHE  THE  SOCIOLOGIST 

and  to  '  pity/  I  am  more  particularly  anxious  to 
express  myself  clearly  on  these  two  points,  inas 
much  as  I  know  how  many  erroneous  opinions 
are  current  in  regard  to  Nietzsche's  attitude 
towards  them.  In  all  gregarious  communities,  as 
is  well  known,  altruism  and  pity  have  become 
very  potent  life-preserving  factors,  and  it  would  be 
hard  to  find  in  Europe  to-day,  a  city,  a  town,  or  a 
village,  in  which  these  two  qualities  are  not  con 
sidered  the  most  creditable  of  virtues.  Now, 
apart  from  the  fact  that  this  excessive  praise  of 
compassion  and  selflessness  is  a  sign  of  slave 
values  being  in  the  ascendant,  we  must  bear  in 
mind  two  things :  (1)  that  under  our  present 
system  of  society,  in  which  cruelties  are  per 
petrated  far  more  brutal  than  any  that  could  be 
found  in  antiquity,  a  sort  of  maudlin  sentimen 
tality  has  arisen  among  the  oppressing  classes, 
whereby  they  attempt  to  counterbalance  their 
deeds  of  oppression  with  lavish  acts  of  charity. 
This  sentimentality  is  a  sign  that  their  conscience 
is  no  longer  clean  for  the  act  of  oppressing ; 
because  in  their  heart  of  hearts  they  feel  them 
selves  unworthy  of  being  at  the  top :  (2)  that 
wherever  two  or  three  human  beings  collect 
together,  a  certain  modicum  of  altruism  and 
compassion  is  a  prerequisite  of  their  social  unity. 

87 


NIETZSCHE 

Dismissing  observation  one  as  the  mere  expres 
sion  of  a  regrettable  fact  which  scarcely  requires 
substantiation,  and  which  is  responsible  for  more 
than  three-quarters  of  the  anomalies  that  char 
acterise  modern  Western  civilisation  ;  and  passing 
over  the  suggestion  that  the  excessive  praise  of 
compassion  and  selflessness  denotes  an  ascendency 
of  slave  values  (for  we  have  dealt  with  this  ques 
tion  in  Chapter  in.),  let  us  turn  to  the  more 
abstract  proposition  enunciated  in  observation 
two  and  try  to  grasp  Nietzsche's  treatment 
of  it. 

In  the  first  place,  let  us  understand  that  there 
are  two  kinds  of  pity  and  selflessness,  just  as 
there  are  two  kinds  of  generosity.  There  is  the 
pity,  the  selflessness  and  the  generosity  which  is 
preached  and  praised  as  a  virtue  by  him  who 
urgently  requires  them  because  he  is  ill-consti 
tuted,  needy,  and  hungry ;  and  there  is  the  pity, 
the  selflessness  and  the  generosity  which  suggests 
itself  to  the  man  overflowing  with  health,  trust  in 
the  future,  and  confidence  in  his  own  powers.  To 
such  a  man,  pity,  selflessness,  and  generosity  are 
a  means  of  discharging  a  certain  plenitude  of 
power,  and  in  his  case  giving  and  bestowing  are 
natural  functions.  In  the  first  instance,  the 
three  virtues  are  preached  from  a  utilitarian 

88 


NIETZSCHE  THE  SOCIOLOGIST 

standpoint  which  tends  to  increase  an  undesirable 
type;  in  the  second,  they  are  the  sign  of  the 
existence  of  a  desirable  type. 

Let  us  hear  Nietzsche — 

'  A  man  who  says :  "  I  like  that,  I  take  it  for  my 
own,  and  mean  to  guard  it  and  protect  it  from 
every  one " ;  and  the  man  who  can  conduct  a 
case,  carry  out  a  resolution,  remain  true  to  an 
opinion,  keep  hold  of  a  woman,  punish  and  over 
throw  insolence ;  a  man  who  has  his  indignation 
and  his  sword,  and  to  whom  the  weak,  the  suffer 
ing,  the  oppressed,  and  even  the  animals  will 
ingly  submit  and  naturally  belong;  in  short,  a 
man  who  is  a  master  by  nature — when  such  a 
man  has  sympathy,  well !  that  sympathy  has 
value !  But  of  what  account  is  the  sympathy  of 
those  who  suffer !  or  of  those  even  who  preach 
sympathy  ! '  l 

Wherever  we  find  anything  akin  to  'pity/  even  in 
nature:  the  suckling  of  the  young,  the  maintenance 
of  dependants  (the  lion's  attitude  towards  the 
jackal),  the  protection  of  the  helpless  young  (as 
in  many  fish  and  mammals),  it  is  always  the 
superabundance  of  the  giver  and  his  Will  to 
Power  which  creates  the  pitiful  act. 

But  the  pity  which  most  of  us  understand  as 

1  O.  E.,  p.  257. 
89 


NIETZSCHE 

virtue  in  Europe  to-day,  is  merely  a  sort  of 
sickly  sensitiveness  and  irritability  towards  pain, 
an  etteminate  absence  of  control  in  the  presence 
of  suffering,  which  has  nothing  whatever  to  do 
with  our  powers  of  alleviating  the  misery  we 
contemplate,  and  which  is  only  compatible  either 
with  excessive  sentimentality  or  with  weak  and 
overstrained  nerves.  In  that  case  all  it  does  is 
to  add  to  the  misery  of  this  world,  and  to  elevate 
to  a  virtue  that  which  is  perhaps  one  of  the 
saddest  signs  of  the  times.  It  is  then  indis 
criminate,  rash,  and  short-sighted,  and  gives  rise 
to  more  evil  than  it  tries  to  dispel. 

'  Ah,  where  in  the  world  have  there  been  greater 
follies  than  with  the  pitiful  ?  And  what  in  the 
world  hath  caused  more  suffering  than  the  follies 
of  the  pitiful  ? 

4  Woe  unto  all  loving  ones  who  have  not  an 
elevation  which  is  above  their  pity ! ' 1 

The  legislator  or  the  leader  (and  it  is  to  him, 

remember,  that  Nietzsche  appeals),  is  often  obliged 

to  leave  dozens  to  die  by  the  wayside,  and  has  to 

do  so  with  a  clean  conscience.     If  themarchjie 

is  organising  requires  certain  sacrifices,  he  must 

be  ready  to  make  them ;   the  slavish  pity,  then, 

which  would  sacrifice  the  greater  to  the  less,  must 

1  Z.,  pp.  104, 105. 

90 


NIETZSCHE  THE  SOCIOLOGIST 

have  been  overcome  by  him  in  his  own  heart, 
and  he  must  have  learnt  that  hardness  which  is 
wider  in  its  sympathies,  more  presbyopic  in  its 
love,  and  less  immediate  in  its  effect.  But  he 
alone  can  feel  like  this  who  has  something  to  give 
to  those  he  leads,  i.e.  his  protection  and  guidance, 
hispromise  ofjt  better  ]and. 

'  Myself  I  would  sacrifice  to  my  design,  and  my 
neighbour  as  well — such  is  the  language  of 
creators. 

'  All  creators,  however,  are  hard.' 1 

Now  turning  to  the  question  of  egoism  cru  et 
vert,  which,  according  to  some,  is  the  very  basis 
and  core  of  Nietzscheism,  what  are  the  points 
which  strike  us  most  in  Nietzsche's  standpoint  ? 
To  begin  with,  in  this  question,  as  in  all  others, 
his  honesty  is  paramount,  and  we  become  con 
scious  of  it  the  moment  we  read  his  first  line  on 
the  subject.  Where  Nietzsche  discusses  matters 
of  which  others  are  wont  to  speak  with  heaving 
breasts,  florid  language,  and  tearful  voices,  he 
takes  particular  pains  to  be  clear,  concise,  cal 
culating  and  cold — hence  perhaps  the  hatred  he 
has  provoked  in  those  who  depend  for  their  effect 
upon  the  impression  of  benevolence  which  their 
watery  eyes,  their  cracked,  good-natured  voices, 
1  z.,  105. 


NIETZSCHE 

and  their  high-falutin'  words  make  upon  a 
multitude. 

Nietzsche  puts  his  finger  on  the  very  centre  of 
the  question  of  egoism.  He  simply  says:  'Not 
every  one  has  the  right  to  be  an  egoist.  Whereas 
in  some  egoism  would  be  a  virtue,  in  others  it 
may  be  an  insufferable  vice  which  should  be 
stamped  out  at  all  costs.' 

In  whom  then  is  egoism  a  vice  ? 

Obviously  in  him  who  is  physiologically  botched, 
below  mediocrity  in  spirit  and  body,  mean,  de 
spicable,  and  even  ugly. 

Egoism  in  such  a  man  means  concentrating 
certain  interests,  and  not  always  the  least  valu 
able,  upon  the  promotion  and  enhancement  of  an 
undesirable  element  in  society.  The  egoism  of 
him  who  is  below  mediocrity  is  a  form  of  tyranny 
which  leads  to  nothing,  save,  perhaps,  a  Heaven 
where  the  haute  volte  will  consist  of  the  whole 
scum  and  dross  of  humanity.  Such  egoism  leads 
humanity  downwards :  it  practically  says :  '  I,  the 
bungled  and  the  botched,  I  the  poor  in  spirit  and 
body,  I  the  mean,  despicable  and  ugly,  want  my 
kind  to  be  all-important,  paramount  and  on  the 
top — I  the  least  desirable  wish  to  prevail/  But 
this  egoism  would  mean  humanity's  ruin,  it 
would  mean  humanity's  suicide  and  annihilation: 
92 


NIETZSCHE  THE  SOCIOLOGIST 

it  would  certainly  mean  humanity's  degradation. 
When  such  egoism  says :  '  I  will  have  all/  the 
only  decent  retort  is  deafness.     When  such  egoism 
says :  '  I  have  as  much  right  to  live  and  flourish 
as  the  well-constituted,  the  superior  in  spirit  and  , 
body,  the  beautiful  and  the  happy/  wisdom  replies  1 
with  a  shrug  of  its  shoulders.     And  when  such 
egoism  preaches  altruism — then !   Then  woe  to  all 
those  who  are  tempted  to  practise  one  virtue  more ! 
Woe  to  humanity !     Woe  to  the  whole  world ! 

There  is,  on  the  other  hand,  a  form  of  egoism, 
which  is  both  virtuous  and  noble.  It  is  the 
egoism  of  him  whose  multiplication  would  make 
the  world  better,  more  desirable,  happier,  healthier, 
superior  in  spirit  and  body.  Egoism  in  such  a 
case  is  a  moral  duty ;  wherever,  in  such  a  case, 
giving,  bestowing — altruism  in  fact — is  not  com 
patible  with  survival,  then  egoism  becomes  the 
highest  principle  of  all,  and  it  is  in  such  circum 
stances  that  altruism  may  become  a  vice. 
Now  let  us  hear  Nietzsche's  own  words : — 
'  Selfishness/  he  says,  '  has  as  much  value  as 
the  physiological  value  of  him  who  possesses  it : 
it  may  be  very  valuable  or  it  may  be  vile  and 
contemptible.  Each  individual  may  be  looked 
at  with  respect  to  whether  he  represents  an 
ascending  or  a  descending  line  of  life.  When 
93 


NIETZSCHE 

that  is  determined,  we  have  a  canon  for  deter 
mining  the  value  of  his  selfishness.  If  he  re 
present  the  ascent  in  the  line  of  life,  his  value  is 
in  fact  very  great — and  on  account  of  the  collec 
tive  life  which  in  him  makes  a  further  step,  the 
concern  about  his  maintenance,  about  providing 
his  optimum  of  conditions,  may  even  be  extreme. 
...  If  he  represent  descending  development, 
decay,  chronic  degeneration,  or  sickening,  he  has 
little  worth,  and  the  greatest  fairness  would  have 
him  take  away  as  little  as  possible  from  the  well- 
\  constituted.  He  is  then  no  more  than  their  parasite.'1 
x  This  is  all  clear  enough ;  but  it  is  quite  con 
ceivable  that  a  misunderstanding  of  it  might  lead 
to  the  most  perverted  notions  of  what  Nietzsche 
actually  stood  for,  and  when  I  hear  people  in 
veighing  against  the  so-called  egoism  of  his 
teaching,  and  declaring  it  poisonous  on  that 
account,  I  often  wonder  whether  they  have  really 
made  any  attempt  at  all  to  comprehend  the  above 
passage,  and  whether  there  is  not  perhaps  some 
thing  wrong  with  language  itself,  that  a  thought 
which  to  some  seems  expressed  so  clearly  and 
unmistakably,  should  still  prove  confusing  and 
incomprehensible  to  others. 

Speaking  once    more  to    higher    men,    then, 
1  The  Twilight  of  the  Idols,  Par.  10,  Aph.  33. 

94 


NIETZSCHE  THE  SOCIOLOGIST 

Nietzsche  tells  them,  with  some  reason  on  his 
side,  that  altruism  may  be  their  greatest  danger, 
that  altruism  may  be  even  their  greatest  tempta 
tion,  that  there  are  times  when  they  must  avoid 
it  as  they  would  avoid  a  plague.  In  periods  of 
gestation,  when  plans  and  dreams  of  plans  for 
the  elevation  of  themselves  and  their  fellows  are 
taking  shape  in  their  minds,  altruism  may  lure 
them  sideways,  it  may  make  them  diverge  from 
their  path,  and  it  may  make  mankind  one  great 
thought  the  poorer.  In  this  sense,  and  in  this 
sense  alone,  does  our  author  deprecate  the  al 
truistic  virtues ;  but,  again,  I  venture  to  remind 
readers  that  it  is  the  simplest  thing  on  earth  to 
awaken  suspicion  against  him  by  declaring,  as 
some  have  declared,  that  his  deprecation  of  y* 
altruism  applies  to  all. 

No  greater  nonsense  could  be  talked  about 
Nietzsche  than  to  say  that  he  preached  universal 
egoism.  Universal  egoism  as  opposed  to  select 
egoism  is  behind  all  the  noisiest  movements  to 
day — it  is  behind  Socialism,  Democracy,  Anarchy, 
and  Nihilism — but  it  is  not  behind  Nietzscheism, 
and  nobody  who  reads  him  with  care  could  ever 
think  so. 

With  these  observations  in  mind,  we  can  read 
the  following  passages  from  Thus  Spake  Zara- 
95 


NIETZSCHE 

thustra  without  either  surprise  or  indignation; 
indeed  we  may  even  learn  a  new  valuation  from 
them  which  will  alter  our  whole  outlook  on  life, 
though  no  such  sudden  revulsion  of  feeling  need 
necessarily  follow  a  study  of  Nietzsche's  doctrine. 
Only  when  we  have  given  his  thoughts  time  to 
become  linked  up  and  co-ordinated  in  our  minds 
are  we  likely  to  find  that  our  view  of  the  world  has 
become  in  the  least  degree  transformed. 

'  Do  I  advise  you  to  love  your  neighbour  ? 
Rather  do  I  advise  you  to  flee  from  your  neigh 
bour  and  to  love  the  most  remote. 

'^Higher  than  love  to  your  neighbour  is  love 
unto  the  most  remote  future  man. 

'  It  is  the  more  remote  (your  children  and  your 
children's  children)  who  pay  for  your  love  unto 
your  neighbour.1 

'  Your  children's  land  ye  shall  love  (be  this  love 
your  new  nobility  !),  the  land  undiscovered  in  the 
remotest  sea !  For  it  I  bid  your  sails  seek  and 
seek! 

'  In  your  children  ye  shall  make  amends  for 
being  the  children  of  your  fathers :  all  the  past 
shall  ye  thus  redeem  !  This  new  table  do  I  place 
over  you  ! ' 2 

1  Z.,  pp.  69,  70.  a  ^.,p.  248. 

96 


SUMMARY  AND  CONCLUSION 


SUMMARY    AND    CONCLUSION 

WHEN  we  have  done  rubbing  our  eyes  and  ears  at 
the  dazzling  and  startling  novelty  of  all  we  have 
seen  and  heard,  let  us  ask  ourselves  calmly  and 
dispassionately  what  sort  of  man  this  is  who  has 
led  us  thus  far !  into  regions  which,  from  their 
very  unfamiliarity  and  exoticness,  may  have 
seemed  to  us  both  unpleasant  and  forbidding. 

This  is  no  time  for  apologetics,  or  for  pleading 
extenuating  circumstances.  Even  if  Nietzsche's 
doctrines  have  been  presented '  in  a  form  I  too  un 
diluted  to  be  inviting,  it  would  scarcely  mend 
matters,  now,  to  beg  pardon  for  them ;  ;and  I  have 
no  intention  of  doing  anything  of  the  sort.  But 
these  questions  may  be  put  without  any  fear  of 
assuming  a  penitential  attitude,  and  I  do  not 
hesitate  to  put  them  :  Was  the  promise  of  Nietz 
sche's  life  fulfilled  ?  Did  the  task  he  started  out 
with, '  the  elevation  of  the  type  man,'  receive  his 
best  strength,  his  best  endeavours,  his  sincerest 
application?  However  fundamentally  we  may 
G  97 


NIETZSCHE 

disagree  with  his  conclusions,  were  they  reached 
by  means  of  an  upright  attempt) at  grappling  with 
the  problems  ?  To  all  of  these  questions  there  is 
but  one  answer,  and  that  answer  clears  Nietzsche 
of  all  the  slander  and  calumny  to  which  he  has 
been  submitted  j  for  the  last  thirty  years. 

However  often  we  may  think  he  has  erred,  it  is 
nonsense  any  longer  to  speak  of  him  as  an 
anarchist,  an  advocate  of  brutality,  a  supporter  of 
immorality  in  its  worst  modern  sense,  and  a 
guardian  saint  of  savage  passions.  If  I  have  led 
any  readers  to  suspect  that  he  was  all  this,  I  can 
only  entreat  them  to  turn  as  soon  as  possible  to 
the  original  works  themselves,  and  there  they  will 
find  that  it  was  I  who  was  wrong. 

Personally  I  believe,  as  Hippolyte  Taine,  Dr. 
George  Brandes  and  Wagner  believed,  that  Nietz 
sche's  work  is  greater  than  his  own  or  the  next 
generation  could  ever  suspect.  Questions  such  as 
Art,  the  future  of  Science,  and  the  future  of 
Religion,  which  Nietzsche  treats  with  his  customary 
skill,  I  have  been  unable  to  find  room  for,  in  this 
work.  But  in  each  of  these  departments,  I  believe 
(and  in  this  belief  I  am  by  no  means  alone)  that 
Nietzsche's  speculations  may  prove  of  the  very 
highest  value. 

Already  in  Biology  there  are  signs  that  Nietz- 
98 


SUMMARY  AND  CONCLUSION 

sche's  conclusions  are  gaining  ground.  In  Art,  as 
I  hope  to  be  able  to  show  elsewhere,  his  doctrines 
are  likely  to  effect!  a  salutary  revolution:  while,  in 
the  departments  of  history,  psychology,  1  juris 
prudence  and  metaphysics,  specialists  will  doubt 
less  arise  who  will  attempt  to  make  innovations 
under  his  leadership. 

For  the  present,  though  the  outlook  is  brighter 
than  it  was,  Nietzscheism — that  is  to  say :  free- 
spiritedness, !  intellectual  bravery  ;  the  ability  to 
stand  alone  when  every  one  else  j  has  his  arm 
linked  j  in  something ;  I  the  courage  to  face  un 
pleasant,  fatal,  >and  disconcerting  truths, — has  not 
much  hope  of  very  general  acceptance,  among 
those  to  whom  it  really  ought  to  appeal.  Calumny," 
which  had  a  long  start, 'has  deafened  many  to  the 
cause  and  will  continue  deafening  a  larger  number 
still,  until  the  truth  is  ultimately  known.  Yet  it 
is  to  be  hoped  that  readers  may  learn  to  be  less 
satisfied  than  they  have  been  heretofore  with 
second-hand  accounts  of  what  Nietzsche  stood 
for,  and  that  very  shortly  everybody  who  is  in-__ 
terested  in  the  matter  will  be  able  to  reply  to  the 
slanderer  with  facts  culled  from  Nietzsche's  life 
and  works. 

*  Mine  enemies  have  grown  strong,'  says  Zara- 
99 


NIETZSCHE 

thustra,  '  and  have  disfigured  the  face  of  my 
teaching,  so  that  my  dearest  friends  have  to  blush 
for  the  gifts  I  gave  them.' 1 

'  But  like  a  wind  I  shall  one  day  blow  amidst 
them,  and  take  away  their  breath  with  my  spirit ; 
thus  my  future  willeth  it. 

'Verily  a  strong  wind  is  Zarathustra^to  all  low 
lands ;  |and  his  enemies  and  everything  that 
spitteth  and  spewethlhe  counselleth  with  such 
advice :  Beware  of  spitting  against  the  wind/ 2 

1  Z.,pp.  95,  96.  2  Z.,  p.  116. 


TOO 


BOOKS  USEFUL  TO  THE  STUDENT 
OF  NIETZSCHE 

BIOGRAPHIES  : — 

Das  Leben  Friedrich    Nietzsche's,   by  Mrs.   Forster- 

Nietzsche. 

Erinnerungen  an  Friedrich  Nietzsche,  by  Deussen. 
Nietzsche,  sein  Leben  und  sein  Werk,  by  Kaoul  Richler. 

EDITIONS  OF  WORKS. 

The  complete  works  of  Friedrich  Nietzsche.  Edited 
by  Dr.  Oscar  Levy.  (The  first  complete  and  authorised 
English  Translation.)  T.  N.  Foulis,  21  Paternoster 
Square. 

Friedrich  Nietzsche's  Werke.     Library  Edition  15  vols. 

Pocket  Edition  (very  good)  10  vols. 

MONOGRAPHS. 

Belart,  Nietzsche's  Ethik. 

Nietzsche's  Metaphysik. 

Nietzsche  und  Richard  Wagner. 

Brandes,  G.,  Menschen  und  Werke. 
Common,  Thos.,  Nietzsche  as  Critic. 
Fouill^e,  A.,  Nietzsche  et  I'Immoralisme. 
Gaultier,  J.,  De  Kant  &  Nietzsche. 

Nietzsche  et  la  Rtforme  philosophique. 

Kennedy,  J.  M.,  The  Quintessence  of  Nietzsche. 
IOI 


NIETZSCHE 

Lichtenberger,  H.,  La  Philosophie  de  Nietzsche. 

Miigge,  Nietzsche  His  Life  and  Works. 

Sera,  Leo,  On  the  Tracks  of  Life. 

Tienes,  Nietzsche's  Stellung  zu  den  Grundfragen  der 

Ethik  genetisch  dargestellt. 
Tille,  A.,  Von  Darwin  bis  Nietzsche. 
Zeitler,  J.,  Nietzsche's  Aesthetik. 


NIETZSCHE'S  WORKS  :   Authorised  Version  :    edited  by  Dr. 
Oscar  Levy. 


Thoughts  out   of  Season.     2 
vols.     5s.  net. 

The  Birth  of  Tragedy.  2s.  Qd. 
net. 

Thus  Spake  Zarathustra.     6s. 
net. 

Beyond     Good     and      Evil. 
3s.  6d.  net. 

The  Future  of  our  Educational 
Institutions.     2s.  Qd.  net. 


Human,    All    too    Human. 
Vol.  i.     5s.  net. 

The  Will  to  Power.     2  vols. 
10s.  net. 

The    Genealogy    of    Morals. 
3s.  Qd.  net. 

The    Case    against    Wagner. 
Is.  net. 

The  Joyful  Wisdom.    5s.  net. 
The  Dawn  of  Day.     5s.  net. 


The  Revival  of  Aristocracy.      By  Dr.  Oscar    Levy. 
3s.  Qd.  net. 

Who  is  to  be  Master  of  the  World  ?    By  A.  M.  Ludovici 
2s.  Qd.  net. 


Printed  by  T.  and  A.  CONSTABLE,  Printers  to  His  Majesty 
at  the  Edinburgh  University  Press 


University  of  Toronto 
Library 


DO  NOT 

REMOVE 

THE 

CARD 

FROM 

THIS 

POCKET 


Acme  Library  Card  Pocket 
LOWE-MARTIN  CO.  LIMITED