Skip to main content

Full text of "A history of the mathematical theory of probability : from the time of Pascal to that of Laplace"

See other formats


University  of  California  •  Berkeley 


Gift  of 


MRS.  GRIFFITH  C.  EVANS 


^1-^^  l^i  cLu^o^  !'^' 


HISTORY    OF 


THE    THEORY    OF    PROBABILITY. 


A    HISTOEY 


OF   THE 


MATHEMATICAL  THEORY  OF  PROBABILITY 


T 


FROM  THE   TIME  OF  PASCAL    TO   TEAT 

OF  LAPLACE. 


BY 


I.  TODHUNTEH,   M.A.,   F.RS. 


1 


.O 


\XYr  O'  C   P  .    UlMOAy^^  ^ 


(Q^aml)til5ge  nnti  Hoution: 
MACMILLAN    AND    CO. 

I86^ 


CambritJcjc: 

PRINTED    BY    C.   J.   CLAY.   M.A. 
AT  THE  UNIVERSITY    PRESS. 


PREFACE. 


The  favourable  reception  which  has  been  granted  to  my  History 
of  the  Calculus  of  Variations  daring  the  Xineteenth  Century  has 
encouraged  me  to  undertake  another  work  of  the  same  kind. 
The  subject  to  which  I  now  invite  attention  has  high  claims  to 
consideration  on  account  of  the  subtle  problems  which  it  involves, 
the  valuable  contributions  to  analysis  which  it  has  produced,  its 
important  practical  applications,  and  the  eminence  of  those  who 
have  cultivated  it. 

The  nature  of  the  problems  which  the  Tlieory  of  Probability 
contemplates,  and  the  influence  which  this  Theory  has  exercised 
on  the  progress  of  mathematical  science  and  also  on  the  concerns 
of  practical  life,  cannot  be  discussed  within  the  limits  of  a  Preface ; 
we  may  however  claim  for  our  subject  all  the  interest  wdiicli  illus- 
trious names  can  confer,  by  the  simple  statement  that  nearly 
every  gi-eat  mathematician  within  the  range  of  a  century  and  a 
half  will  come  before  us  in  the  course  of  the  history.  To  mention 
only  the  most  distinguished  in  this  distinguished  roll — we  sliall 
find  here — Pascal  and  Format,  worthy  to  be  associated  by  kindred 
genius  and  character— De  Moivre  with  his  rare  powers  of  analysis, 
which  seem  to  belong  only  to  a  later  epoch,  and  which  justify  the 
honour  in  which  he  was  held  by  Newton — Leibnitz  and  the  emi- 
nent school  of  which  he  may  be  considered  the  founder,  a  school 
including  the  Bernoullis  and  Euler — D'Alembert,  one  of  the  most 
conspicuous  of  those  who  brought  on  the  French  revolution,  and 
Condorcet,  one  of  the  most  illustrious  of  its  victims — Lagrange 
and  Laplace  who  survived  until  the  present  century,  and  may  be 
regarded  as  rivals  at  that  time  for  the  suj^remacy  of  the  mathe- 
matical world. 

I  will  now  give  an  outline  of  the  contents  of  the  book. 

The  first  Chapter  contains  an  account  of  some  anticipations 
of  the  subject  which  are  contained  in  the  writings  of  Cardan, 
Kepler  and  Galileo. 

The  second  Chapter  introduces  the  Chevalier  de  Mere'  who 
having  puzzled  himself  in  vain  over  a  problem  in  chances, 
fortunately  turned  for  help  to  Pascal :  the  Problem  of  Points  is 
discussed  in  the  correspondence  between  Pascal  and  Format,  and 
thus  the  Theory  of  Probability  begins  its  career. 


Vi  PREFACE. 

The  third  Chapter  analyses  the  treatise  in  which  Huygens  in 
1659  exhibited  what  was  then  known  of  the  subject.  Works  such 
as  this,  which  present  to  students  the  opportunity  of  becoming 
acquainted  with  the  speculations  of  the  foremost  men  of  the 
time,  cannot  be  too  highly  commended ;  in  this  respect  our  sub- 
ject has  been  fortunate,  for  the  example  which  was  afforded  by 
Huygens  has  been  imitated  by  James  Bernoulli,  De  Moivre  and 
Laplace — and  the  same  course  might  with  great  advantage  be 
pursued  in  connexion  with  other  subjects  by  mathematicians  in 
the  present  day. 

The  fourth  Chapter  contains  a  sketch  of  the  early  history  of 
the  theory  of  Permutations  and  Combinations  ;  and  the  fifth  Chap- 
ter a  sketch  of  the  early  history  of  the  researches  on  Mortality 
and  Life  Insurance.  Neither  of  these  Chapters  claims  to  be  ex- 
haustive ;  but  they  contain  so  much  as  may  suffice  to  trace  the 
connexion  of  the  branches  to  which  they  relate  with  the  main  sub- 
ject of  our  history. 

The  sixth  Chapter  gives  an  account  of  some  miscellaneous  in- 
vestigations between  the  years  1670  and  1700.  Our  attention  is 
directed  in  succession  to  Caramuel,  Sauveur,  James  Bernoulli, 
Leibnitz,  a  translator  of  Huygens's  treatise  whom  I  take  to  be 
Arbuthnot,  Roberts,  and  Craig — the  last  of  whom  is  notorious  for 
an  absurd  abuse  of  mathematics  in  connexion  with  the  probability 
of  testimony. 

The  seventh  Chapter  analyses  the  Ars  Conjectandi  of  James 
Bernoulli.  This  is  an  elaborate  treatise  by  one  of  the  greatest 
mathematicians  of  the  age,  and  although  it  was  unfortunately 
left  incomplete,  it  affords  abundant  evidence  of  its  author's  ability 
and  of  his  interest  in  the  subject.  Especially  we  may  notice  the 
famous  theorem  which  justly  bears  the  name  of  James  Bernoulli, 
and  which  places  the  Theory  of  Probability  in  a  more  commanding 
position  than  it  had  hitherto  occupied. 

The  eighth  Chapter  is  devoted  to  Montmort.  He  is  not  to  be 
compared  for  mathematical  power  with  James  Bernoulli  or  De 
Moivre;  nor  does  he  seem  to  have  formed  a  very  exalted  idea  of 
the  true  dignity  and  importance  of  the  subject.  But  he  was  en- 
thusiastically devoted  to  it;  he  spai^ed  no  labour  himself,  and  his 
influence  direct  or  indirect  stimulated  the  exertions  of  Nicolas 
Bernoulli  and  of  De  Moivre. 

The  ninth  Chapter  relates  to  De  Moivre,  containing  a  full 
analysis  of  his  Doctrine  of  Chances,  De  Moivre  brought  to  bear 
on  the  subject  mathematical  powers  of  the  highest  order ;  these 
powers  are  especially  manifested  in  the  results  which  he  enun- 
ciated respecting  the  great  problem  of  the  Duration  of  Play. 
Unfortunately  he  did  not  publish  demonstrations,  and  Lagrange 


PREFACE.  Vii 

himself  more  than  fifty  years  later  found  a  good  exercise  for  his 
analytical  skill  in  supplying  the  investigations  ;  this  circumstance 
compels  us  to  admire  De  Moivre's  powers,  and  to  regret  the  loss 
which  his  concealment  of  his  methods  has  occasioned  to  mathe- 
matics, or  at  least  to  mathematical  history. 

De  Moivre's  Doctrine  of  Chances  formed  a  treatise  on  the 
subject,  full,  clear  and  accurate  ;  and  it  maintained  its  place  as  a 
standard  work,  at  least  in  England,  almost  down  to  our  own  day. 

The  tenth  Chapter  gives  an  account  of  some  miscellaneous 
investigations  between  the  years  1700  and  17-30.  These  inves- 
tio-ations  are  due  to  Nicolas  Bernoulli,  Arbuthnot,  Browne,  Mairan, 
Nicole,  Buffon,  Ham,  Thomas  Simpson  and  John  Bernoulli. 

The  eleventh  Chapter  relates  to  Daniel  Bernoulli,  containing 
an  account  of  a  series  of  memoirs  published  chiefly  in  the  volumes 
of  the  Academy  of  Petersburg ;  the  memoirs  are  remarkable  for 
boldness  and  originality,  the  first  of  them  contains  the  celebrated 
theory  of  Moral  Expectation. 

The  twelfth  Chapter  relates  to  Euler ;  it  gives  an  account  of 
his  memoirs,  which  relate  j^rincipally  to  certain  games  of  chance. 

The  thirteenth  Chapter  relates  to  D'Alembert ;  it  gives  a  full 
account  of  the  objections  which  he  urged  against  some  of  the 
fundamental  principles  of  the  subject,  and  of  his  controversy  with 
Daniel  Bernoulli  on  the  mathematical  investisj-ation  of  the  ^ain  to 
human  life  which  would  arise  from  the  extirpation  of  one  of  the 
most  fatal  diseases  to  which  the  human  race  is  liable. 

The  fourteenth  Chapter  relates  to  Bayes  ;  it  explains  the  me- 
thod by  which  he  demonstrated  his  famous  theorem,  which  may 
be  said  to  have  been  the  origin  of  that  part  of  the  subject  which 
relates  to  the  probabilities  of  causes  as  inferred  from  observed 
effects. 

The  fifteenth  Chapter  is  devoted  to  Lagrange ;  he  contributed 
to  the  subject  a  valuable  memoir  on  the  theory  of  the  errors  of 
observations,  and  demonstrations  of  the  results  enunciated  by  De 
Moivre  respecting  the  Duration  of  Play. 

The  sixteenth  Chapter  contains  notices  of  miscellaneous  inves- 
tigations between  the  years  1750  and  17^0.  This  Chapter  brings 
before  us  Kaestner,  Clark,  Mallet,  John  Bernoulli,  Beguelin, 
Michell,  Lambert,  Buffon,  Fuss,  and  some  others.  The  memoir 
of  Michell  is  remarkable ;  it  contains  the  famous  argument  for  the 
existence  of  design  drawn  from  the  fact  of  the  closeness  of  certain 
stars,  like  the  Pleiades. 

The  seventeenth  Chapter  relates  to  Cordorcet,  who  published  a 
large  book  and  a  long  memoir  upon  the  Theory  of  Probability. 
He  chiefly  discussed  the  probability  of  the  correctness  of  judg- 
ments determined  by  a  majority  of  votes  ;  he  has  the  merit  of  first 


vlii  PREFACE. 

submitting   this  question  to  mathematical  investigation,  but   his 
own  results  are  not  of  great  practical  importance. 

The  eighteenth  Chapter  relates  to  Trembley.  He  wrote  several 
memoirs  with  the  main  design  of  establishing  by  elementary 
methods  results  which  had  been  originally  obtained  by  the  aid  of 
the  higher  branches  of  mathematics ;  but  he  does  not  seem  to 
have  been  very  successful  in  carrying  out  his  design. 

The  nineteenth  Chapter  contains  an  account  of  miscellaneous 
investigations  between  the  years  1780  and  1800.  It  includes-  the 
following  names  ;  Borda,  Malfatti,  Bicquilley,  the  writers  in  the 
mathematical  portion  of  the  Encydopedie  Methodique,  D'Anieres, 
Waring,  Prevost  and  Lhuilier,  and  Young. 

The  twentieth  Chapter  is  devoted  to  Laplace  ;  this  contains  a 
full  account  of  all  his  writings  on  the  subject  of  Probability.  First 
his  memoirs  in  chronological  order,  are  analysed,  and  then  the  great 
work  in  which  he  embodied  all  his  own  investigations  and  much 
derived  from  other  writers.  1  hope  it  will  be  found  that  all  the 
parts  of  Laplace's  memoirs  and  work  have  been  carefully  and 
clearly  expounded ;  I  would  venture  to  refer  for  examples  to 
Laplace's  method  of  approximation  to  integrals,  to  the  Problem  of 
Points,  to  James  Bernoulli's  theorem,  to  the  problem  taken  from 
Buffon,  and  above  all  to  the  famous  method  of  Least  Squares. 
With  respect  to  the  last  subject  I  have  availed  myself  of  the 
guidance  of  Poisson's  luminous  analysis,  and  have  given  a  general 
investigation,  applying  to  the  case  of  more  than  one  unknown 
element.  I  hope  I  have  thus  accomplished  something  towards  ren- 
dering the  theory  of  this  important  method  accessible  to  students. 

In  an  Appendix  I  have  noticed  some  writings  which  came 
under  my  attention  during  the  printing  of  the  work  too  late  to  be 
referred  to  their  proper  places. 

I  have  endeavoured  to  be  quite  accurate  in  my  statements, 
and  to  reproduce  the  essential  elements  of  the  original  works 
which  I  have  analysed.  I  have  however  not  thought  it  indispen- 
sable to  preserve  the  exact  notation  in  which  any  investigation 
w^as  first  presented.  It  did  not  appear  to  me  of  any  importance 
to  retain  the  specific  letters  for  denoting  the  known  and  unknown 
quantities  of  an  algebraical  problem  which  any  writer  may  have 
chosen  to  use.  Very  often  the  same  problem  has  been  dis- 
cussed by  various  writers,  and  in  order  to  compare  their  methods 
with  any  facility  it  is  necessary  to  use  one  set  of  symbols  through- 
out, although  each  writer  may  have  preferred  his  peculiar  set. 
In  fact  by  exercising  care  in  the  choice  of  notation  I  believe  that 
my  exposition  of  contrasted  methods  has  gained  much  in  brevity 
and  clearness  without  any  sacrifice  of  real  fidelity. 

I  have  used  no  symbols  which  are  not  common  to  all  mathc- 


PREFACE.  IX 

matical  literature,  except  \n  wliicli  is  an  abbreviation  for  the  pro- 
duct 1 .  2,  ...'?i, frequently  but  not  universally  employed  :  some  such 
symbol  is  much  required,  and  I  do  not  know  of  any  which  is  pre- 
ferable to  this,  and  I  have  accordingly  introduced  it  in  all  my 
publications. 

There  are  three  important  authors  whom  I  have  frequently 
cited  whose  works  on  Probability  have  passed  through  more  than 
one  edition,  Montmort,  De  Moivre,  and  Laplace :  it  may  save  trouble 
to  a  person  who  may  happen  to  consult  the  present  volume  if  I 
here  refer  to  pages  79,  13G,  and  495  where  I  have  stated  which 
editions  I  have  cited. 

Perhaps  it  may  appear  that  I  have  allotted  too  much  space  to 
some  of  the  authors  whose  works  I  examine,  especially  the  more 
ancient ;  but  it  is  difficult  to  be  accurate  or  interesting  if  the  nar- 
rative is  confined  to  a  mere  catalogue  of  titles  :  and  as  experience 
shews  that  mathematical  histories  are  but  rarely  undertaken,  it 
seems  desirable  that  they  should  not  be  executed  on  a  meagre 
and  inadequate  scale. 

I  will  here  advert  to  some  of  my  predecessors  in  this  depart- 
ment of  mathematical  history ;  and  thus  it  will  appear  that  I  have 
not  obtained  much  assistance  from  them. 

In  the  third  volume  of  Montucla's  Histoire  des  Mathematiqiies 
pages  380—426  are  devoted  to  the  Theory  of  Probability  and  the 
kindred  subjects.  I  have  always  cited  this  volume  simply  by  the 
name  Montucla,  but  it  is  of  course  well  known  that  the  third  and 
fourth  volumes  were  edited  from  the  author's  manuscripts  after  his 
death  by  La  Landc.  I  should  be  sorry  to  apj^ear  ungrateful  to 
Montucla;  his  work  is  indispensable  to  the  student  of  mathema- 
tical history,  for  whatever  may  be  its  defects  it  remains  without 
any  rival.  But  I  have  been  much  disappointed  in  what  he  says 
respecting  the  Theory  of  Probability ;  he  is  not  copious,  nor  accu- 
rate, nor  critical.  Hallaui  has  characterised  him  with  some  severity, 
by  saying  in  reference  to  a  point  of  mathematical  history,  "  Mon- 
tucla is  as  superficial  as  usual :"  see  a  note  in  the  second  Chapter 
of  the  first  volume  of  the  History  of  the  Literature  of  Europe. 

There  are  brief  outlines  of  the  history  involved  or  formally 
incorporated  in  some  of  the  elementary  treatises  on  the  Theory 
of  Probability :  I  need  notice  only  the  best,  which  occurs  in  the 
Treatise  on  Probability  published  in  the  Library  of  L^seful  Know- 
ledge. This  little  work  is  anonymous,  but  is  known  to  have  been 
written  by  Lubbock  and  Drinkwater ;  the  former  is  now  Sir  John 
Lubbock,  aud  the  latter  changed  his  name  to  Drinkwater-Bethune : 
see  Professor  De  Morgan's  Arithmetical  Books...  page  106,  a  letter 
by  him  in  the  Assurance  Magazine,  Yol.  TX.  page  238,  and  another 
letter  by  him  in  the  Times,  Dec.  16,  1862.     The  treatise  is  inter- 


X  PREFACE. 

esting  and  valuable,  but  I  have  not  been  able  to  agree  uniformly 
with  the  historical  statements  which  it  makes  or  implies. 

A  more  ambitious  work  bears  the  title  Histoire  dii  Calcul 
des  Prohabilites  depuis  ses  origines  jusqud  nos  jours  par  Charles 
Gouraud...  Paris,  184^8.  This  consists  of  148  widely  printed  octavo 
pages ;  it  is  a  popular  narrative  entirely  free  from  mathematical 
symbols,  containing  however  some  important  specific  references. 
Exact  truth  occasionally  suffers  for  the  sake  of  a  rhetorical  style 
unsuitable  alike  to  history  and  to  science;  nevertheless  the  general 
reader  will  be  gratified  by  a  lively  and  vigorous  exhibition  of  the 
whole  course  of  the  subject.  M.  Gouraud  recognises  the  value  of 
the  purely  mathematical  part  of  the  Theory  of  Probability,  but 
will  not  allow  the  soundness  of  the  applications  which  have  been 
made  of  these  mathematical  formulse  to  questions  involving  moral 
or  political  considerations.  His  history  seems  to  be  a  portion  of  a 
very  extensive  essay  in  three  folio  volumes  containing  1929  pages 
written  when  he  was  very  young  in  competition  for  a  prize  pro- 
posed by  the  French  Academy  on  a  subject  entitled  Theorie  de  la 
Certitude;  see  the  Rapport  by  M.  Franck  in  the  Seances  et  Tra- 
vaux  de  V Academie  des  Sciences  morales  et  politiques,  Vol.  x. 
pages  372,  382,  and  Vol.  XI.  page  139.  It  is  scarcely  necessary 
to  remark  that  M.  Gouraud  has  gained  distinction  in  other  branches 
of  literature  since  the  publication  of  his  work  which  we  have  here 
noticed. 

There  is  one  history  of  our  subject  which  is  indeed  only  a 
sketch  but  traced  in  lines  of  light  by  the  hand  of  the  great 
master  himself:  Laplace  devoted  a  few  pages  of  the  introduction 
to  his  celebrated  work  to  recording  the  names  of  his  predecessors 
and  their  contributions  to  the  Theory  of  Probability.  It  is  much 
to  be  regretted  that  he  did  not  supply  specific  references  through- 
out his  treatise,  in  order  to  distinguish  carefully  between  that 
which  he  merely  transmitted  from  preceding  mathematicians  and 
that  which  he  originated  himself. 

It  is  necessary  to  observe  that  in  cases  where  I  point  out  a 
similarity  between  the  investigations  of  two  or  more  writers  I  do 
not  mean  to  imply  that  these  investigations  could  not  have  been 
made  independently.  Such  coincidences  may  occur  easily  and 
naturally  without  any  reason  for  imputing  unworthy  conduct  to 
those  who  succeed  the  author  who  had  the  priority  in  publication. 
I  draw  attention  to  this  circumstance  because  I  find  with  regret 
that  from  a  passage  in  my  former  historical  work  an  inference  has 
been  drawn  of  the  kind  which  I  here  disclaim.  In  the  case  of  a 
writer  Uke  Laplace  who  agrees  with  his  predecessors,  not  in  one  or 
two  points  but  in  very  many,  it  is  of  course  obvious  that  he  must 
have  borrowed  largely,   and   we   conclude  that  he   supposed   the 


PREFACE.  XI 

erudition   of  his  contemporaries  would  be   sufficient  to  prevent 
them  from  ascribing  to  himself  more  than  was  justly  due. 

It  will  be  seen  that  I  have  ventured  to  survey  a  very  extensive 
field  of  mathematical  research.  It  has  been  mv  aim  to  estimate 
carefully  and  impartially  the  character  and  the  merit  of  tlie 
numerous  memoirs  and  works  which  I  have  examined;  my  criti- 
cism has  been  intentionally  close  and  searching,  but  I  trust  never 
irreverent  nor  unjust.  I  have  sometimes  explained  fully  the 
errors  which  I  detected;  sometimes,  when  the  detailed  exposition 
of  the  error  would  have  recpiired  more  space  than  the  matter 
deserved,  I  have  given  only  a  brief  indication  which  may  be 
serviceable  to  a  student  of  the  original  production  itself  I  have 
not  hesitated  to  introduce  remarks  and  developments  of  my 
own  whenever  the  subject  seemed  to  require  them.  In  an 
elaborate  German  review  of  my  former  puljlication  on  mathe- 
matical history  it  was  suggested  that  my  own  contributions  were 
too  prominent,  and  that  the  purely  historical  character  of  the 
work  was  thereby  impaired;  but  I  have  not  been  induced  to 
change  my  plan,  for  I  continue  to  think  that  such  additions  as  I 
have  been  able  to  make  tend  to  render  the  subject  more  in- 
telligible and  more  complete,  without  disturbing  in  any  serious 
degree  the  continuity  of  the  history.  I  cannot  venture  to  expect 
that  in  such  a  difficult  subject  I  shall  be  quite  free  from  error 
either  in  my  exposition  of  the  labours  of  others,  or  in  my  own 
contributions;  but  I  hope  that  such  failures  will  not  be  numerous 
nor  important.  I  shall  receive  most  gratefully  intimations  of  any 
errors  or  omissions  whicli  may  be  detected  in  the  work. 

I  have  been  careful  to  corroborate  mv  statements  bv  exact 
quotations  from  the  originals,  and  these  I  have  given  in  the  lan- 
guages in  which  they  were  published,  instead  of  translating  them  ; 
the  course  which  I  have  here  adopted  is  I  understand  more  agree- 
able to  foreign  students  into  whose  hands  the  book  may  fall.  I 
have  been  careful  to  preserve  the  historical  notices  and  references 
which  occurred  in  the  works  I  studied ;  and  by  the  aid  of  the 
Table  of  Contents,  the  Chronological  List,  and  the  Index,  which 
accompany  the  present  volume,  it  will  be  easy  to  ascertain  with 
regard  to  any  proposed  mathematician  down  to  the  close  of  the 
eighteenth  century,  whether  he  has  written  au}'thing  upon  the 
Theory  of  Probability. 

I  have  carried  the  history  down  to  the  close  of  the  eighteenth 
century ;  in  the  case  of  Laplace,  however,  I  have  passed  beyond  this 
limit:  but  by  far  the  larger  part  of  his  labours  on  the  Theory  of 
Probability  were  accomplished  during  tlie  eighteenth  century, 
though  collected  and  republished  by  him  in  his  celebrated  work  in 
the  early  part  of  the  present  century,  and  it  was  therefore  conve- 


Xll  PREFACE. 

nient  to  include  a  full  account  of  all  his  researches  in  the  present 
volume.  There  is  ample  scope  for  a  continuation  of  the  work 
which  should  conduct  the  history  through  the  period  which  has 
elapsed  since  the  close  of  the  eighteenth  century ;  and  I  have 
already  made  some  progress  in  the  analysis  of  the  rich  materials. 
But  when  I  consider  the  time  and  labour  expended  on  the  present 
volume,  although  reluctant  to  abandon  a  long  cherished  design, 
I  feel  far  less  sanguine  than  once  I  did  that  I  shall  have  the 
leisure  to  arrive  at  the  termination  I  originally  ventured  to  pro- 
pose to  myself 

Although  I  wish  the  present  work  to  be  regarded  princijDally  as 
a  history,  yet  there  are  two  other  aspects  under  which  it  may 
solicit  the  attention  of  students.  It  may  claim  the  title  of  a  com- 
prehensive treatise  on  the  Theory  of  Probability,  for  it  assumes 
in  the  reader  only  so  much  knowledge  as  can  be  gained  from 
an  elementary  book  on  Algebra,  and  introduces  him  to  almost 
every  process  and  every  species  of  problem  which  the  literature  of 
the  subject  can  furnish;  or  the  work  may  be  considered  more  spe- 
cially as  a  commentary  on  the  celebrated  treatise  of  Laplace, — 
and  perhaps  no  mathematical  treatise  ever  more  required  or  more 
deserved  such  an  accompaniment. 

My  sincere  thanks  are  due  to  Professor  De  Morgan,  himself 
conspicuous  among  cultivators  of  the  Theory  of  Probability,  for 
the  kind  interest  which  he  has  taken  in  my  work,  for  the  loan  of 
scarce  books,  and  for  the  suggestion  of  valuable  references.  A 
similar  interest  was  manifested  by  one  prematurely  lost  to  science, 
whose  mathematical  and  metaphysical  genius,  attested  by  his 
marvellous  work  on  the  Laws  of  Thought,  led  him  naturally  and 
rightfully  in  that  direction  which  Pascal  and  Leibnitz  had  marked 
with  the  unfading  lustre  of  their  approbation;  and  who  by  his 
rare  ability,  his  wide  attainments,  and  his  attractive  character, 
gained  the  affection  and  the  reverence  of  all  who  knew  him. 

I.  TODHUNTER. 

Cambridge, 
May,  1865. 


CONTENTS. 


PAGE 


Chapter  I.    Cardan.   Kepler.    Galileo  .        .        l 

Commentary  on  Dante,  i.  Cardan,  Be  Ludo  Alece,  i,  Kepler,  De  Stella 
Nova,  4.     Galileo,  Considerazione  sopra  il  Giuco  del  Dadi,  4  ;  Lettcre,  5. 

Chapter  II.    Pascal  and  Fermat    ....        7 

Quotations  from  Laplace,  Poisson,  and  Boole,  7.  De  Mare's  Problems,  7, 
Problem  of  Points,  9.  De  Merc's  dissatisfaction,  11.  Opinion  of  Leib- 
nitz, 12.  Fermat's  solution  of  the  Problem  of  Points,  13.  Roberval,  13. 
Pascal's  error,  14.  The  Arithmetical  Triangle,  17.  Pascal's  design,  20. 
Contemporary  mathematicians,  21. 

Chapter  III.    Huygens 22 

De  liatiodniis  in  Ludo  Alece,  22.  English  translations,  23.  Huygens's  solu- 
tion of  a  problem,  24  ;  Problems  proposed  for  solution,  25. 

Chapter  IV.    On  Combinations       .        .        .        .20 

"William  Buckley,  26.  Bernardus  Bauhusius  and  Erycius  Puteanus,  27.  Quo- 
tation from  James  Bernoulli,  28.  Pascal,  29.  Schooten,  30.  Leibnitz, 
Dissertaiio  de  Arte  Comhinatoria,  31  ;  his  fruitless  attempts,  33.  Wallis'3 
Algebra,  34;  his  errors,  35. 

Chapter  V.    Mortality  and  Life  Insurance        .      37 

John  Graunt,  37.  Van  Hudden  and  John  de  Witt,  38,  Sir  William  Petty,  39. 
Correspondence  between  Leibnitz  and  James  Bernoulli,  40.  Halley,  4 1  ; 
his  table,  42  ;  geometrical  illustration,  43. 

Chapter  YI.    Miscellaneous  Investigations  between 

THE  YEARS  1670  AND  1700 -ii 

Caramuel's  Matliesis  Biceps,  44  ;  his  errors,  45,  46.  Sauveur  on  Bassette,  46. 
James  Bernoulli's  two  problems,  47.  Leibnitz,  47;  his  error,  48.  Of 
the  Laws  of  Chance,  ascribed  to  Motte,  48 ;  really  by  Arbuthnot,  49  ; 
quotation  from  the  preface,  50 ;  error,  52  ;  problem  proposed,  53. 
Francis  Roberts,  An  Arithmetical  Paradox,  53,  Craig's  Theologies  Chris- 
tiance  Principia  Maihematica,  54.     Credihility  of  Human  Testimony,  55. 

Chapter  YII.    Jaihes  Bernoulli      .        .        .        .56 

Correspondence  with  Leibnitz,  56  ;  Ars  Conjectandi,  57.  Error  of  Montucia,  ^S. 
Contents  of  the  Ars  Conjectandi,  58.  Problem  of  Points,  59.  James 
Bernoulli's  own  method  for  problems  on  chances,  60;  his  solution  of  a 


XIV  CONTENTS. 

PAGE 

problem  on  Duration  of  Play,  6i ;  he  points  out  a  plausible  mistake,  63; 
treats  of  Permutations  and  Combinations,  64 ;  his  Numbers,  65 ;  Pro- 
blem of  Points,  66  ;  his  problem  with  a  false  but  plausible  solution,  67  ; 
his  famous  Theorem,  71 ;  memoir  on  infinite  series,  73;  letter  on  the  game 
of  Tennis,  75.   Gouraud's  opinion,  77. 

Chapter  VIII.    Montmoet 78 

Fontenelle's  Eloge,  78.  Two  editions  of  Montmort's  book,  79 ;  contents  of  the 
book,  80;  De  Moivre's  reference  to  Montmort,  81;  Montmort  treats 
of  Combinations  and  the  Binomial  Theorem,  82  ;  demonstrates  a  formula 
given  by  De  Moivre,  84  ;  sums  certain  Series,  86 ;  his  researches  on  Pha- 
raon,  87;  Treize,  91;  Bassette,  93.  Problem  sob  ed  by  a  lady,  95.  Pro- 
blem of  Points,  96;  Bowls,  100;  Duration  of  1  lay,  loi ;  Her,  106; 
Tas,  no.  Letter  from  John  Bernoulli,  113.  Nicolas  Bernoulli's  game  of 
chance,  116.  Treize,  120.  Summation  of  Series,  121.  Waldegrave's 
problem,  122,  Summation  of  Series,  125.  Malebranche,  126.  Pascal,  128. 
Sum  of  a  series,  129.  Argument  by  Arbuthnot  and  's  Gravesande  on 
Divine  Providence,  130.  James  Bernoulli's  Theorem,  131.  Montmort's 
views  on  a  History  of  Mathematics,  132.  Problems  by  Nicolas  Ber- 
noulli, 133.      Petersburg  Problem,  134. 

Chapter  IX.    De  Moivre 135 

Testimony  of  John  Bernoulli  and  of  Newton,  135.  Editions  of  the  Doc- 
trine of  Chances,  136.  De  Mensura  Sortis,  137.  De  Moivre's  approximate 
formula,  138;  his  Lemma,  138;  Waldegrave's  problem,  139;  Duration 
of  Play,  140;  Doctrine  of  Chances,  141;  Litroduction  to  it,  142;  con- 
tinued fractions,  143;  De  Moivre's  approximate  formula,  144;  Duration 
of  Play,  147;  Woodcock's  problem,  147;  Bassette  and  Pharaon,  150; 
Numbers  of  Bernoulli,  151;  Pharaon,  152;  Treize  or  Rencontre,  153; 
Bowls,  159;  Problem  on  Dice,  160;  Waldegrave's  problem,  162; 
Hazard,  163;  Whist,  164;  Piquet,  166;  Dirration  of  Play,  167;  Recur- 
ring Series,  178;  Cuming's  problem,  182  ;  James  Bernoulli's  Theorem,  183  ; 
problem  on  a  Run  of  Events,  184;  Miscellanea  Analytica,  187;  contro- 
versy with  Montmort,  188;  Stirling's  theorem,  189;  Arbuthnot's  argu- 
ment, 193. 

Chapter  X.    Miscellaneous  Investigations  BET^yEEN 

THE  YEARS  1700  AND  1750 191? 

Nicolas  Bernoulli,  194.  Barbeyrac,  196.  Arbuthnot's  argument  on  Divine 
Providence,  197.  Waldegrave's  problem,  199.  Browne's  translation  of 
Huygens's  treatise,  199.  Mairan  on  Odd  and  Even,  200.  Nicole,  201. 
BufFon,  203.  Ham,  203.  Trente-et-quarante,  205.  Simpson's  Nature  and 
Laws  of  Chance,  206;  he  adds  something  to  De  Moivre's  results,  207; 
sums  certain  Series,  210;  his  Miscellaneous  Tracts,  ■21 1.  Problem  by  John 
Bernoulli,  212. 


CONTENTS.  XV 

PAGB 

Chapter  XL    Daniel  Bernoulli      .        .        .        .213 

Theory  of  Moral  Expectation,  213;  Petersburg  Problem,  220;  Inclination  of 
planes  of  Planetary  Orbits,  122  ;  Small-pox,  224;  mean  dm-ation  of  mar- 
riages, 229;  Daniel  Bernoulli's  problem,  231  ;  Births  of  boys  and  girls,  235; 
Errors  of  observations,  236, 

Chapter  XIL    Euler 239 

Treize,  239;  Mortality,  240;  Annuities,  242;  Pharaon,  243;  Lottery,  2^5; 
Lottery,  247;  notes  on  Lagrange,  249;  Lottery,  250;  Life  Assurance,  256. 

Chapter  XIII.    D'Alembert 258 

Croix  ou  Pile,  258;  Petersburg  Problem,  259;  Small-pox,  265;  Petersburg 
Problem,  275;  Mathematical  Expectation,  276;  Inoculation,  277;  Croix 
ou  Pile,  279;  Petersburg  Problem,  280;  Inoculation,  282;  refers  to 
Laplace,  287;  Petersburg  Problem,  288;  error  in  a  problem,  290. 

Chapter  XI Y.    Bates 2.94 

Bayes's  theorem,  295;  his  mode  of  investigation,  296;  area  of  a  curve,  298. 
Price's  example,  299.    Approximations  to  an  area,  300, 

Chapter  XV.    Lagrange 301 

Theory  of  errors,  301;  Recurring  Series,  313;  Problem  of  Points,  315;  Dura- 
tion of  Play,  316;  Annuities,  320. 

Chapter  XVI.    Miscellaneous  Investigations  be- 
tween the  years  iToO  AND  1780         .         .         .321 

Kaestner,  321.  Dodson,  322.  Hoyle,  322.  Clark's  Laics  of  CJiauce,  323. 
Mallet,  325,  John  Bernoulli,  325.  Beguelin,  on  a  Lottery  problem,  3 28  ; 
on  the  Petersburg  Problem,  332.  Michell,  332.  John  Bernoulli,  335. 
Lambert,  335.  Mallet,  337.  Emerson,  343.  Buffon,  on  gambling,  344 ; 
ou  the  Petersburg  Problem,  345  ;  his  own  problem,  347.    Fuss,  349. 

Chapter  XVIL    Condorcet 351 

Dlscours  Preliminaire,  351;  Essai,  353;  first  Hj-pothesis,  353;  second  Hypo- 
thesis, 357;  problem  on  a  Run  of  Events,  361 ;  election  of  candidates  for 
an  ofl&ce,  370;  problems  on  inverse  probability,  37S;  Risk  which  may  be 
neglected,  3S6 ;  Trial  by  Jury,  388;  advantageous  Tribunals,  391;  ex- 
pectation, 392  ;  Petersburg  Problem,  393 ;  evaluation  of  feudal  rights,  395  ; 
probability  of  future  events,  398;  extraordinary  facts,  400;  credibility 
of  Roman  History,  406.   Opinions  on  Condorcet's  merits,  409. 


XVI  CONTENTS. 

PAGR 

Chapter  XVIII,    Teembley      .        .        .        .    •    .    411 

Problem  of  Points,  412;  probability  of  causes,  413;  problem  of  births,  415; 
lottery  problem,  421;  small-pox,  423;  duration  of  marriages,  426;  theory 
of  errorS;  428 ;  Her,  429. 

Chapter  XIX.    Miscellaneous  Investigations  be- 
tween the  years  1780  AND  1800       .        .        .     432 

Prevost,  432.  BorJa,  432.  Malfatti,  434.  Bicquilley,  438.  Encyclopedie  Me- 
tkodique,  441.  D'Anieres,  445,  Waring,  446.  Ancillon,  453.  Prevost  and 
Lhuilier,  45 3.   Young,  463. 

Chapter  XX.    Laplace 464 

Memoirs  of  1774,  464;  recurring  series,  464;  Duration  of  Play,  465;  Odd 
and  Even,  465;  probability  of  causes,  465  ;  theory  of  errors,  468;  Peters- 
burg Problem,  470;  Memoir  of  1773,  473;  Odd  and  Even,  473;  Problem 
of  Points,  474 ;  Duration  of  Play,  474 ;  Inclination  of  Orbits  of  Comets,  475 ; 
Memoir  of  1781,  476  ;  Duration  of  Play,  476;  approximation  to  integrals, 
478;  problem  of  births,  482;  theory  of  errors,  484;  Memoir  of  1779,  484  ;. 
Generating  Functions,  484;  Memoir  of  1782,  485;  Memoirs  of  1783,  485; 
Memoir  of  1809,  487;  Memoir  of  18 10,  489;  Connaissance  des  Terns,  490; 
Problem  on  Comets,  491;  Theorie...des  Probalilites,  495;  editions  of 
it,  495;  dedication  to  Napoleon,  496;  Laplace's  researches  in  Physical 
Astronomy,  499^  Pascal's  argument,  500;  illusions,  501;  Bacon,  503; 
Livre  I.  505  ;  Generating  Functions,  505  ;  Method  of  approximation,  512  ; 
examples,  516;  Livre  II.  first  Chapter,  527;  second  Chapter  527;  Odd 
and  Even,  527;  Problem  of  Points,  528;  Fourth  Supplement,  532;  Walde- 
grave's  Problem,  535;  Run  of  Events,  539;  Inclination  of  the  Orbits  of 
Planets,  542;  election  of  candidates,  547;  third  Chapter,  548;  James 
Bernoulli's  Theorem,  548;  Daniel  Bernoulli's  problem,  558;  fourth  Chap- 
ter, 560;  Poisson's  problem,  561;  Least  Squares,  571;  history  of  this 
subject,  588;  fifth  Chapter,  589.  BufFon's  problem,  590;  sixth  Chapter,  592; 
a  Definite  Integral,  594;  seventh  Chapter,  598;  eighth  Chapter,  601  ; 
Small-pox,  60 r;  duration  of  marriages,  602;  ninth  Chapter,  605  ;  exten- 
sion of  James  Bernoulli's  Theorem,  607 ;  tenth  Chapter,  609 ;  inequal- 
ity, 609;  eleventh  Chapter,  609;  first  Supplement,  610;  second  Supple- 
ment, 611;  third  Supplement,  612;  quotation  fi-om  Poisson,  613. 

Appendix     . 614 

John  de  Witt,  614.   Rizzetti,  614.    Kahle,  615.    's  Gravesande,  616.    Quotation 
from  John  Bernoulli,  616.    Mendelsohn,  616.    Lhuiher,  618.  Waring,  618. 


r 


CHAPTER   I. 

CARDAN.     KEPLER.     GALILEO. 

1.  The  practice  of  games  of  chance  must  at  all  times  have 
directed  attention  to  some  of  the  elementary  considerations  of  the 
Theory  of  Probability.  Libri  finds  in  a  commentary  on  the  Divina 
Commedia  of  Dante  the  earliest  indication  of  the  different  proba- 
bility of  the  various  throws  which  can  be  made  with  three  dice. 
The  passage  from  the  commentary  is  quoted  by  Libri ;  it  relates  to 
the  first  line  of  the  sixth  canto  of  the  Purgatorio.  The  com- 
mentary was  published  at  Venice  in  1477.  See  Libri,  Histoire 
des  Sciences  Mathematiques  en  Italie,  Vol.  ii.  p.  188. 

2.  Some  other  intimations  of  traces  of  our  subject  in  older 
writers  are  given  by  Gouraud  in  the  following  passage,  unfor- 
tunately without  any  precise  reference. 

Les  anciens  paraissent  avoir  eutierement  ignore  cette  sorte  de  calcul. 
L'eruditioii  moderne  en  a,  il  est  vrai,  trouve  quelques  traces  dans  un 
poeme  en  latin  barbare  intitule  :  De  Vetidq,  oeuvre  d'un  nioine  du  Bas- 
Empire,  dans  un  commentaire  de  Dante  de  la  fin  du  XY^  siecle,  et 
dans  les  ecrits  de  plusieurs  matliematiciens  italiens  du   moyeu   age  et 

de  la   renaissance,  Pacioli,  Tartaglia,  Peverone ; Go\irsi\\d,IIisto{re 

du  Calcul  des  Frohahilites,  page  3. 

3.  A  treatise  by  Cardan  entitled  De  Ludo  Alece  next  claims 
our  attention.  This  treatise  was  published  in  1663,  in  the  first 
volume  of  the  edition  of  Cardan's  collected  works,  long  after 
Cardan's  death,  which  took  -place  in  1576. 

1 


2  CARDAN. 

Montmort  says,  "  Jerome  Cardan  a  donne  un  Traits  De  Ludo 
Alese ;  mais  on  n'y  trouve  que  de  I'erudition  et  des  reflexions 
morales."  Essai  d'Analyse.-.ip.  XL.  Libri  says,  "Cardan  a  ecrit 
un  traite  special  de  Ludo  Alece,  ou  se  trouvent  resolues  plusieurs 
questions  d'analyse  combinatoire."  Histoire,  Vol.  ill.  p.  176.  The 
former  notice  ascribes  too  little  and  the  latter  too  much  to 
Cardan. 

4.  Cardan's  treatise  occupies  fifteen  folio  pages,  each  containing 
two  columns;  it  is  so  badly  printed  as  to  be  scarcely  intelligible. 
Cardan  himself  was  an  inveterate  gambler  ;  and  his  treatise  may 
be  best  described  as  a  gambler's  manual.  It  contains  much  mis- 
cellaneous matter  connected  with  gambling,  such  as  descriptions  of 
games  and  an  account  of  the  precautions  necessary  to  be  employed 
in  order  to  guard  against  adversaries  disposed  to  cheat :  the 
discussions  relating  to  chances  form  but  a  small  portion  of  the 
treatise. 

5,  As  a  specimen  of  Cardan's  treatise  we  will  indicate  the 
contents  of  his  thirteenth  Chapter.  He  shews  the  number  of 
cases  which  are  favourable  for  each  throw  that  can  be  made  with 
two  dice.  Thus  two  and  twelve  can  each  be  thrown  in  only  one 
way.  Eleven  can  be  thrown  in  two  ways,  namely,  by  six  appear- 
ing on  either  of  the  two  dice  and  five  on  the  other.  Ten  can  be 
thrown  in  three  ways,  namely,  by  five  a23pearing  on  each  of  the 
dice,  or  by  six  appearing  on  either  and  four  on  the  other.  And 
so  on. 

Cardan  proceeds,  *'Sed  in  Ludo  fritilli  undecim  puncta  adjicere 
decet,  quia  una  Alea  potest  ostendi."...The  meaning  apparently  is, 
that  the  person  who  throws  the  two  dice  is  to  be  considered  to 
have  thrown  a  given  number  when  one  of  the  dice  alone  exhibits 
that  number,  as  well  as  when  the  number  is  made  up  by  the  sum 
of  the  numbers  on  the  two  dice.  Hence,  for  six  or  any  smaller 
number  eleven  more  ftivourablc  cases  arise  besides  those  already 
considered. 

Cardan  next  exhibits  correctly  the  number  of  cases  which  are 
favourable  for  each  throw  that  can  be  made  with  three  dice.  Thus 
three  and  eighteen  can  each  be  thrown  in  only  one  way  ;  four  and 


CARDAN,  3 

seventeen  can  each  be  thrown  in  three  ways  ;  and  so  on.  Cardan 
also  gives  the  following  list  of  the  number  of  cases  in  Fritillo  : 

12         34         5  6789       10     11     12 

108     111     115     120     12G     133     33     36     37     36     33     26 

Here  we  have  corrected  two  misprints  by  the  aid  of  Cardan's 
verbal  statements.  It  is  not  obvious  what  the  table  means.  It 
might  be  supposed,  in  analogy  with  what  has  already  been  said, 
that  if  a  person  throws  three  dice  he  is  to  be  considered  to  have 
thrown  a  given  number  when  one  of  the  dice  alone  exhibits  that 
number,  or  when  two  dice  together  exhibit  it  as  their  sum,  as 
well  as  when  all  the  three  dice  exhibit  it  as  their  sum  :  and  this 
would  agree  wdth  Cardans  remark,  that  for  numbers  higher  than 
twelve  the  favourable  cases  are  the  same  as  those  already  given  by 
him  for  three  dice.  But  this  meaning  does  not  agree  with  Cardan's 
table ;  for  with  this  meaning  we  should  proceed  thus  to  find  the 
cases  favourable  for  an  ace :  there  are  5^  cases  in  which  no  ace 
appears,  and  there  are  6'  cases  in  all,  hence  there  are  6^  —  5^  cases 
in  which  we  have  an  ace  or  aces,  that  is  91  cases,  and  not  108  as 
Cardan  gives. 

The  connexion  between  the  numbers  in  the  ordinary  mode  of 
using  dice  and  the  numbers  which  Cardan  gives  appears  to 
be  the  following.  Let  n  be  the  number  of  cases  which  are  favour- 
able to  a  given  throw  in  the  ordinary  mode  of  using  three  dice, 
and  N  the  number  of  cases  favourable  to  the  same  throw  in 
Cardan's  mode  ;  let  m  be  the  number  of  cases  favourable  to  the 
given  throw  in  the  ordinary  mode  of  using  two  dice.  Then  for  any 
throw  not  less  than  thirteen,  N=n  ;  for  any  throw  between  seven  and 
twelve,  both  inclusive,  N  =  Sni  +  n ;  for  any  throw  not  greater  than 
six,  i\^=  108  +  3?/i  +  n.  There  is  only  one  deviation  from  this  law  ; 
Cardan  gives  26  favourable  cases  for  the  throw  twelve,  and  our 
proposed  law  would  give  3  +  25,  that  is  28. 

We  do  not,  however,  see  what  simple  mode  of  playing  with 
three  dice  can  be  suo'o-ested  which  shall  oive  favourable  cases 
agreeing  in  number  with  those  determined  by  the  above  law. 

6.     Some  further   account  of  Cardan's  treatise  will  be  found 

1—2 


^  KEPLER. 

in  the  Life  of  Cardan,  by  Henry  Moiiey,  Vol.  I.  pages  92 — 95. 
Mr  Morley  seems  to  misunderstand  the  words  of  Cardan  which  he 
quotes  on  his  page  92,  in  consequence  of  which  he  says  that 
Cardan  "  lays  it  down  coolly  and  philosophically,  as  one  of  his  first 
axioms,  that  dice  and  cards  ought  to  be  played  for  money."  In 
the  passage  quoted  by  Mr  Morley,  Cardan  seems  rather  to  admit 
the  propriety  of  moderation  in  the  stake,  than  to  assert  that  there 
must  be  a  stake;  this  moderation  Cardan  recommends  elsewhere, 
as  for  example  in  his  second  Chapter.  Cardan's  treatise  is  briefly 
noticed  in  the  article  Prohability  of  the  English  Cyclopcedia. 

7.  Some  remarks  on  the  subject  of  chance  were  made  by 
Kepler  in  his  work  De  Stella  Kova  in  pede  Serjjentarii,  which  was 
published  in  1606.  Kepler  examines  the  different  opinions  on  the 
cause  of  the  appearance  of  a  new  star  which  shone  with  great 
splendour  in  1604,  and  among  these  opinions  the  Epicurean  notion 
that  the  star  had  been  produced  by  the  fortuitous  concurrence 
of  atoms.  The  whole  passage  is  curious,  but  we  need  not  repro- 
duce it,  for  it  is  easily  accessible  in  the  reprint  of  Kepler's  works 
now  in  the  course  of  publication  ;  see  Joannis  Kepleri  Astronomi 
Opera  Omnia  edidit  Dr  Ch.  Frisch,  Vol.  ii.  pp.  714 — 716.  See 
also  the  Life  of  Kepler  in  the  Library  of  Useful  Knoiuledge,  p.  13. 
The  passage  attracted  the  attention  of  Dugald  Stewart ;  see  his 
Works  edited  by  Hamilton,  Vol.  I.  p.  617. 

A  few  words  of  Kepler  may  be  quoted  as  evidence  of  the 
soundness  of  his  opinions  ;  he  shows  that  even  such  events  as 
throws  of  dice  do  not  happen  without  a  cause.     He  says, 

Quare  hoc  jactu  Venus  cecidit,  illo  canis  1  Nimh'um  lusor  liac  vice 
tessellam  alio  latere  arripuit,  aliter  marm  condidit,  aliter  intus  agitavit, 
alio  impetii  animi  maniisve  projecit,  aliter  interflavit  aura,  alio  loco 
alvei  imj)egit.  JSTihil  hie  est,  quod  sua  causa  sic  caruerit,  si  quis  ista 
subtilia  posset  coiisectavi. 

8.  The  next  investigation  which  we  have  to  notice  is  that  by 
Galileo,  entitled  Consider azione  sopyu  il  Giuco  dei  Dadi.  The  date 
of  this  piece  is  unknown;  Galileo  died  in  1642.  It  appears  that 
a  friend  had  consulted  Galileo  on  the  following  dilBculty :  with 
three  dice  the  number  9  and  the  number  10  can  each  be  produced 
by  six  different  combinations,  and  yet  experience  shows  that  the 


GALILEO.  b 

number  10  is  oftener  thrown  than  the  number  9.  Galileo  makes 
a  careful  and  accurate  analysis  of  all  the  cases  which  can  occur, 
and  he  shows  that  out  of  216  possible  cases  27  are  favourable 
to  the  appearance  of  the  number  10,  and  25  are  favourable  to  the 
appearance  of  the  number  9. 

The  piece  will  be  found  in  Vol.  xiv.  pages  293 — 290,   of  Le 

Opere  cU    Galileo   Galilei,  Firenze,  1855.      From  the  Biblio- 

grafia  Galileiana  given  in  Vol.  XV.  of  this  edition  of  Galileo's 
works  we  learn  that  the  piece  first  aj^peared  in  the  edition  of  the 
works  published  at  Florence  in  1718  :  here  it  occurs  in  Vol.  III. 
pages  119 — 121. 

9.  Libri  in  his  Histoire  des  Sciences  Mathematiques  en  Italie, 
Vol.  IV.  page  288,  has  the  following  remark  relating  to  Galileo  : 
..."Ton  voit,  par  ses  lettres,  qu'il  s'etait  longtemps  occupe  d'une 
question  delicate  et  non  encore  resolue,  relative  h,  la  maniere  de 
compter  les  erreurs  en  raison  geometrique  ou  en  proportion 
arithm^tique,  question  qui  touche  ^galement  au  calcul  des  pro- 
babilites  et  a  Tarithmetique  politique."  Libri  refers  to  Vol.  ii. 
page  00,  of  the  edition  of  Galileo's  works  published  at  Florence 
in  1718  ;  there  can,  however,  be  no  doubt,  that  he  means  Vol.  iii. 
The  letters  will  be  found  in  Vol.  xiv.  pages  231 — 284'  of  Le 
Opere... di  Galileo  Galilei,  Firenze,  1855  ;  they  are  entitled  Lettere 
intorno  la  stwia  di  un  cavallo.  We  are  informed  that  in  those 
days  the  Florentine  gentlemen,  instead  of  wasting  their  time 
in  attention  to  ladies,  or  in  the  stables,  or  in  excessive  eraminfr. 
were  accustomed  to  improve  themselves  by  learned  conversation 
in  cultivated  society.  In  one  of  their  meetings  the  following 
question  was  proposed  ;  a  horse  is  really  worth  a  hundred  crowns, 
one  person  estimated  it  at  ten  crowns  and  another  at  a  thousand  ; 
which  of  the  two  made  the  more  extra  vagrant  estimate  ?  Amoncr 
the  persons  who  were  consulted  was  Galileo  ;  he  pronounced  the 
two  estimates  to  be  equally  extravagant,  because  the  ratio  of  a 
thousand  to  a  hundred  is  the  same  as  the  ratio  of  a  hundred  to 
ten.  On  the  other  hand,  a  priest  named  Nozzolini,  who  was  also 
consulted,  pronounced  the  higher  estimate  to  be  more  extravagant 
than  the  other,  because  the  excess  of  a  thousand  above  a  hundred 
is  gi'eater  than  that  of  a  hundred  above  ten.     Various  letters  of 


6  GALILEO. 

Galileo  and  Nozzolini  are  printed,  and  also  a  letter  of  Benedetto 
Castelli,  who  took  the  same  side  as  Galileo ;  it  appears  that  Galileo 
had  the  same  notion  as  Nozzolini  when  the  question  was  first 
23roposed  to  him,  but  afterwards  changed  his  mind.  The  matter 
is  discussed  by  the  disputants  in  a  very  lively  manner,  and  some 
amusing  illustrations  are  introduced.  It  does  not  appear,  however, 
that  the  discussion  is  of  any  scientific  interest  or  value,  and  the 
terms  in  which  Libri  refers  to  it  attribute  much  more  importance 
to  Galileo's  letters  than  they  deserve.  The  Florentine  gentlemen 
when  they  renounced  the  frivolities  already  mentioned  might  have 
investigated  questions  of  greater  moment  than  that  which  is  here 
brought  under  our  notice. 


CHAPTER   II. 

PASCAL    AND    FERMAT. 

10.  The  indications  which  we  have  given  in  tlie  preceding 
Chapter  of  the  subsequent  Theory  of  Probability  are  extremely 
slight;  and  we  find  that  \vriters  on  the  subject  have  shewn  a  jus- 
tifiable pride  in  connecting  the  true  origin  of  their  science  with 
the  great  name  of  Pascal.     Thus, 

EUe  doit  la  naissance  h  deux  Georaetres  frangais  du  dix-septieme 
si^cle,  si  fecond  en  grands  hommes  et  en  grandes  decouvertes,  et  peut- 
^tre  de  tons  les  siecles  celiii  qui  fait  le  plus  d'honneur  a  I'esprit 
humain.  Pascal  et  Fermat  se  proposerent  et  resolurent  quelqucs  pro- 
blemes  sur  les  probabilites... Laplace,  Tlieorie . . .des  Prob.  1st  edition, 
page  3. 

XJn  probleme  relatif  aux  jeux  de  liasard,  propose  a  un  austere  jan- 
seniste  par  un  homme  du  monde  a  ete  I'origine  du  calcul  des  probabilites. 
Poisson,  Recherches  sur  la  Prob.  page  1. 

The  problem  which  the  Chevalier  de  Mere  (a  reputed  gamester) 
proposed  to  the  recluse  of  Port  Royal  (not  yet  witlidi-awn  from  the  in- 
terests of  science  by  the  more  distracting  contemplation  of  the  "great- 
ness and  the  misery  of  man''),  was  the  first  of  a  long  series  of  problems, 
destined  to  call  into  existence  new  methods  in  matliematical  analvsis, 
and  to  render  valuable  service  in  the  practical  concerns  of  life."  Boole, 
Laws  of  Thought,    page  243. 

11.  It  appears  then  that  the  Chevalier  de  Mere  proposed 
certain  questions  to  Pascal ;  and  Pascal  con^esponded  with  Fer- 
mat on  the  subject  of  these  questions.  Unfortunately  only  a 
portion  of  the  correspondence  is  now  accessible.      Three  letters 


8  PASCAL   AND   FERMAT. 

of  Pascal  to  Format  on  this  subject,  which  were  all  written  in 
165-i,  were  published  in  the  Varia  Opera  Mathematica  D.  Petri 
de  Fer7nat... Tolosse,  1679,  pages  179 — 188.  These  letters  are 
reprinted  in  Pascal's  works ;  in  the  edition  of  Paris,  1819,  they 
occur  in  Yol.  iv.  pages  360 — 888.  This  volume  of  Pascal's  works 
also  contains  some  letters  written  by  Format  to  Pascal,  which  are 
not  given  in  Format's  works ;  two  of  these  relate  to  Probabilities, 
one  of  them  is  in  reply  to  the  second  of  Pascal's  three  letters,  and 
the  other  apparently  is  in  reply  to  a  letter  from  Pascal  which 
has  not  been  preserved  ;  see  pages  385 — 388  of  the  volume. 

We  will  quote  from  the  edition  of  Pascal's  works  just  named. 
Pascal's  first  letter  indicates  that  some  previous  correspondence 
had  occurred  which  we  do  not  possess ;  the  letter  is  dated  July  29, 
1654.     He  begins. 

Monsieur,  L'impatience  me  prend  aussi-bieii  qu  a  vous  ;  et  quoique 
je  sois  encore  au  lit,  je  ne  puis  m'empeclier  de  vous  dire  que  je  re9us 
hier  au  soir,  de  la  part  de  M.  de  Carcavi,  votre  lettre  sur  les  partis, 
que  j'admire  si  fort,  que  je  ne  puis  vous  le  dire.  Je  n'ai  pas  le  loisir  de 
m'etendre ;  mais  en  un  mot  vous  avez  trouve  les  deux  partis  des  des  et 
des  parties  dans  la  parfaite  justesse  :  j'en  suis  tout  satisfait ;  car  je  ne 
doute  plus  maintenant  que  je  ne  sois  dans  la  verite,  apres  la  rencontre 
admirable  oil  je  me  trouve  avec  vous.  J'admire  bien  da  vantage  la 
metliode  des  parties  que  celle  des  des ;  j'avois  vu  plusieurs  personnes 
trouver  celle  des  des,  comme  M.  le  chevalier  de  Mere,  qui  est  celui  qui 
m'a  propose  ces  questions,  et  aussi  M.  de  Roberval ;  mais  M.  de  Mere 
n'avoit  jamais  pu  trouver  la  juste  valeur  des  parties,  ni  de  biais  pour 
y  arriver  :  de  sorte  que  je  me  trouvois  seul  qui  eusse  connu  cette 
proportion. 

Pascal's  letter  then  proceeds  to  discuss  the  problem  to  which  it 
appears  from  the  above  extract  he  attached  the  greatest  importance. 
It  is  called  in  English  the  Problem  of  Points,  and  is  thus  enun- 
ciated :  two  players  want  each  a  given  number  of  points  in  order 
to  win ;  if  they  separate  without  playing  out  the  game,  how 
should  the  stakes  be  divided  between  them  ? 

The  question  amounts  to  asking  what  is  the  probability  which 
each  player  has,  at  any  given  stage  of  the  game,  of  winning  the 
game.      In  the  discussion  between  Pascal  and  Fermat  it  is  sup- 


PASCAL   AND    FERMAT.  9 

posed   that  the  players  have  equal  chances   of  whining  a  single 
point. 

12.  We  will  now  give  an  account  of  Pascal's  investigations 
on  the  Problem  of  Points ;  in  substance  we  translate  his  words. 

The  following  is  my  method  for  determining  the  share  of  each 
player,  when,  for  example,  two  players  play  a  game  of  three  points 
and  each  player  has  staked  32  pistoles. 

Suppose  that  the  first  player  has  gained  two  points  and  the 
second  player  one  point ;  they  have  now  to  play  for  a  point  on 
this  condition,  that  if  the  first  player  gains  he  takes  all  the  money 
which  is  at  stake,  namely  6^  pistoles,  and  if  the  second  player 
gains  each  player  has  two  points,  so  that  they  are  on  terms  of 
equality,  and  if  they  leave  off  playing  each  ought  to  take  32 
pistoles.  Thus,  if  the  first  player  gains,  64  pistoles  belong  to 
him,  and  if  he  loses,  32  pistoles  belong  to  him.  If,  then,  the 
players  do  not  wish  to  play  this  game,  but  to  separate  without 
playing  it,  the  first  player  w^ould  say  to  the  second  "  I  am  certain  of 
32  pistoles  even  if  I  lose  this  game,  and  as  for  the  other  32  pistoles 
perhaps  I  shall  have  them  and  perhaps  you  will  have  them ;  the 
chances  are  equal.  Let  us  then  divide  these  32  pistoles  equally 
and  give  me  also  the  32  pistoles  of  which  I  am  certain."  Thus 
the  first  player  wdll  have  48  pistoles  and  the  second  16  pistoles. 

Next,  suppose  that  the  first  player  has  gained  two  points  and 
the  second  player  none,  and  that  they  are  about  to  play  for  a 
point ;  the  condition  then  is  that  if  the  first  player  gains  this 
point  he  secures  the  game  and  takes  the  64  pistoles,  and  if  the 
second  player  gains  this  point  the  players  will  then  be  in  the 
situation  already  examined,  in  which  the  first  player  is  entitled 
to  48  pistoles,  and  the  second  to  16  pistoles.  Thus  if  they  do  not 
wish  to  play,  the  first  player  would  say  to  the  second  "  If  I  gain 
the  point  I  gain  64  pistoles  ;  if  I  lose  it  I  am  entitled  to  48 
pistoles.  Give  me  then  the  48  pistoles  of  which  I  am  certain, 
and  divide  the  other  16  equally,  since  our  chances  of  gaining  the 
point  are  equal."  Thus  the  first  player  will  have  56  pistoles  and 
the  second  player  8  pistoles. 

Finally,  suppose  that  the  first  player  has  gained  one  point  and 


10  PASCAL   AND   FERMAT. 

the  second  player  none.  If  they  proceed  to  play  for  a  point  the 
condition  is  that  if  the  first  player  gains  it  the  players  will  be  in 
the  situation  first  examined,  in  which  the  first  player  is  entitled  to 
5Q  pistoles  ;  if  the  first  player  loses  the  point  each  player  has  then 
a  point,  and  each  is  entitled  to  32  pistoles.  Thus  if  they  do  not 
wish  to  play,  the  first  player  would  say  to  the  second  "  Give  me 
the  82  pistoles  of  which  I  am  certain  and  divide  the  remainder  of 
the  56  pistoles  equally,  that  is,  divide  24  pistoles  equally."  Thus 
the  first  player  will  have  the  sum  of  32  and  12  pistoles,  that  is 
44  pistoles,  and  consequently  the  second  will  have  20  pistoles. 

13.  Pascal  then  proceeds  to  enunciate  two  general  results 
without  demonstrations.     We  will  give  them  in  modern  notation. 

(1)  Suppose  each  player  to  have  staked  a  sum  of  money 
denoted  by  A  ;  let  the  number  of  points  in  the  game  be  n+  1,  and 
suppose  the  first  player  to  have  gained  n  points  and  the  second 
player  none.     If  the  players  agree  to  separate  without  playing 

A 

any  more  the  first  player  is  entitled  to  2 A  —  ~  . 

(2)  Suppose  the  stakes  and  the  number  of  points  in  the  game 
as  before,  and  suppose  that  the  first  player  has  gained  one  point 
and  the  second  player  none.  If  the  players  agree  to  separate 
without  playing  any  more,  the  first  player  is  entitled  to 

,  1  .  3  .  5  .  .  .  (2n  -  1) 

■^2.4.6...         2/1    • 

Pascal  intimates  that  the  second  theorem  is  difficult  to  prove. 
He  says  it  depends  on  two  propositions,  the  first  of  which  is  purely 
arithmetical  and  the  second  of  which  relates  to  chances.  The 
first  amounts  in  fact  to  the  proposition  in  modern  works  on 
Algebra  which  gives  the  sum  of  the  co-efficients  of  the  terms  in 
the  Binomial  Theorem.  The  second  consists  of  a  statement  of 
the  value  of  the  first  player's  chance  by  means  of  combinations, 
from  which  by  the  aid  of  the  arithmetical  proposition  the  value 
above  given  is  deduced.  The  demonstrations  of  these  two  results 
may  be  obtained  from  a  general  theorem  which  will  be  given  later 
in  the  present  Chapter ;  see  Art.  23.     Pascal  adds  a  table  which 


PASCAL  AND   FERMAT.  11 

exhibits  a  complete  statement  of  all  the  cases  which  can  occur  in 
a  game  of  six  points. 

14.     Pascal  then  proceeds  to  another  topic.     He  says 

Je  n'a  pas  le  temps  de  vous  envoyer  la  demonstration  d'une  difficulte 
qui  etonnoit  fort  M.  de  Mere  :  car  il  a  tres-bon  esprit,  mais  il  n'est  pas 
geometre  ;  c'est,  comme  vous  savez,  un  grand  defaut;  etmeme  ilne  com- 
prend  pas  qu'une  ligne  mathematique  soit  divisible  a  I'infini,  et  croit 
fort  bien  entendre  qu'elle  est  composee  de  points  en  nombre  fini,  et 
jamais  je  n*ai  pu  Ten  tirer ;  si  vous  pouviez  le  faire,  on  le  rendroit 
parfait.  II  me  disoit  done  qu'il  avoit  trouve  faussete  dans  les  nombres 
par  cette  raison. 

The  difficulty  is  the  following.  If  we  undertake  to  throw  a 
six  with  one  die  the  odds  are  in  favour  of  doing  it  in  four  throws, 
being  as  671  to  625  ;  if  we  undertake  to  throw  two  sixes  with  two 
dice  the  odds  are  not  in  favour  of  doing  it  in  twenty-four  throws. 
Nevertheless  24  is  to  86,  which  is  the  number  of  cases  with  two 
dice,  as  4  is  to  6,  which  is  the  number  of  cases  with  one  die. 
Pascal  proceeds 

"Voilk  quel  etoit  son  grand  scandale,  qui  lui  faisoit  dire  hautement 
que  les  propositions  n'etoient  pas  constantes,  et  que  I'arithmetique  se 
d^mentoit.  Mais  vous  en  verrez  bien  aisement  la  raison,  par  les  prin- 
cipes  o^  vous  etes. 

15.  In  Pascal's  letter,  as  it  is  printed  in  Fermat's  works,  the 
name  de  Mere  is  not  given  in  the  passage  we  have  quoted  in  the 
preceding  article  ;  a  blank  occurs  after  the  21.  It  seems,  however, 
to  be  generally  allowed  that  the  blank  has  been  filled  up  correctly 
by  the  publishers  of  Pascal's  works :  Montmort  has  no  doubt  on 
the  matter ;  see  his  p.  XXXII.  See  also  Gouraud,  p.  1 ;  Lubbock 
and  Drinkwater,  p.  41.  But  there  is  certainly  some  difficulty.  For 
in  the  extract  which  we  have  given  in  Art.  11,  Pascal  states  that 
M.  de  Mere  could  solve  one  problem,  celle  des  des,  and  seems  to 
imply  that  he  failed  only  in  the  Problem  of  Points.  Montucla 
says  that  the  Problem  of  Points  w^as  proposed  to  Pascal  by  the 
Chevalier  de  Mer^,  "  qui  lui  en  proposa  aussi  quelques  autres  sur  le 
jeu  de  des,  comme  de  detemiiner  en  combien  de  coups  on  pent 
parier  d'amener  une  rafle,  &c.     Ce  chevalier,  plus  bel  esprit  que 


12  PASCAL   AND   FERMAT. 

geom^tre  ou  analyste,  rdsolut  a  la  verite  ces  derni^res,  qui  ne  sont 
pas  bien  difficiles ;  mais  il  echoua  pour  le  precedent,  ainsi  que 
Roberval,  a  qui  Pascal  le  proposa."  p.  384.  These  words  would 
seem  to  imply  that,  in  Montucla's  opinion,  M.  de  Mere  was  not  the 
person  alluded  to  by  Pascal  in  the  passage  we  have  quoted  in 
Article  14.  We  may  remark  that  Montucla  was  not  justified  in 
suofsrestinof  that  M.  de  Mere  must  have  been  an  indifferent  mathe- 
matician,  because  he  could  not  solve  the  Problem  of  Points ;  for 
the  case  of  Roberval  shews  that  an  eminent  mathematician  at  that 
time  might  find  the  problem  too  difficult. 

Leibnitz  says  of  M.  de  Mere,  "  II  est  vrai  cependant  que  le  Che- 
valier avoit  quelque  genie  extraordinaire,  meme  pour  les  Mathe- 
matiques ;"  and  these  words  seem  intended  seriously,  although  in 
the  context  of  this  passage  Leibnitz  is  depreciating  M.  de  Merd. 
Leibnitii,  Opera  Omnia,  ed.  Dutens,  Vol.  ii.  part  1.  p.  92. 

In  the  Nouveaiix  Essais,  Li  v.  IV.  Chap.  16,  Leibnitz  says, 
*'  Le  Chevalier  de  Mere  dont  les  Agrements  et  les  autres  ouvrages 
ont  ete  imprimes,  homme  d'un  esprit  jDenetrant  et  qui  etoit  joueur 
et  philosophe." 

It  must  be  confessed  that  Leibnitz  speaks  far  less  favourably  of 
M.  de  Mere  in  another  place.  Opera,  Vol.  V.  p.  203.  From  this  pas- 
sage, and  from  a  note  in  the  article  on  Zeno  in  Bayle's  Dictionary, 
to  which  Leibnitz  refers,  it  appears  that  M.  de  Mere  maintained 
that  a  magnitude  was  not  infinitely  divisible  :  this  assists  in  identi- 
fying him  with  Pascal's  friend  who  would  have  been  jDerfect  had  it 
not  been  for  this  single  error. 

On  the  whole,  in  spite  of  the  difficulty  which  we  have  pointed 
out,  we  conclude  that  M.  de  Mer^  really  was  the  person  who  so 
strenuously  asserted  that  the  propositions  of  Arithmetic  were  in- 
consistent with  themselves ;  and  although  it  may  be  unfortunate 
for  him  that  he  is  now  known  principally  for  his  error,  it  is  some 
compensation  that  his  name  is  indissolubly  associated  with  those  of 
Pascal  and  Fermat  in  the  history  of  the  Theory  of  Probability. 

16.  The  remainder  of  Pascal's  letter  relates  to  other  mathe- 
matical topics.  Fermat's  reply  is  not  extant  ;  but  the  nature  of  it 
may  be  inferred  from  Pascal's  next  letter.     It  appears  that  Fermat 


PASCAL   AND    FERMAT.  13 

sent  to  Pascal  a  solution  of  the  Problem  of  Points  depending  on 
combinations. 

Pascal's  second  letter  is  dated  August  24th,  1654.  He  says  that 
Fermat's  method  is  satisfactory  when  there  are  only  two  players, 
but  unsatisfactory  when  there  are  more  than  two.  Here  Pascal 
was  wrong  as  we  shall  see.  Pascal  then  gives  an  example  of 
Fermat's  method,  as  follows.  Suppose  there  are  two  players,  and 
that  the  first  wants  two  points  to  win  and  the  second  three  points. 
The  game  will  then  certainly  be  decided  in  the  course  of  four 
trials.  Take  the  letters  a  and  h  and  write  down  all  the  combina- 
tions that  can  be  formed  of  four  letters.  These  combinations  are 
the  following,  16  in  number  : 


a 

a 

a 

a 

a 

h 

a 

a 

h 

a 

a 

a 

h 

h 

a 

a 

a 

a 

a 

h 

a 

h 

a 

h 

h 

a 

a 

h 

h 

h 

a 

b 

a 

a 

h 

a 

a 

h 

h 

a 

h 

a 

h' 

a 

h 

h 

h 

a 

a 

a 

h 

h 

a 

h 

h 

h 

h 

a 

h 

h 

h 

h 

h 

h 

Now  let  A  denote  the  player  who  wants  two  points,  and  B  the 
player  who  wants  three  points.  Then  in  these  16  combinations 
every  combination  in  which  a  occurs  twice  or  oftener  represents  a 
case  favourable  to  A,  and  every  combination  in  which  h  occurs 
three  times  or  oftener  represents  a  case  favourable  to  B.  Thus  on 
counting  them  it  will  be  found  that  there  are  11  cases  favourable  to 
A,  and  5  cases  favourable  to  B ;  and  as  these  cases  are  all  equally 
likely,  -4's  chance  of  winning  the  game  is  to  -S's  chance  as 
11  is  to  5. 

17.  Pascal  says  that  he  communicated  Fermat's  method  to 
Roberval,  who  objected  to  it  on  the  following  ground.  In  the 
example  just  considered  it  is  supposed  that  four  trials  will  be 
made  ;  but  this  is  not  necessarily  the  case ;  for  it  is  quite  possible 
that  the  first  player  may  win  in  the  next  two  trials,  and  so  the 
game  be  finished  in  two  trials.  Pascal  answers  this  objection  by 
stating,  that  although  it  is  quite  possible  that  the  game  may  be 
finished  in  two  trials  or  in  three  trials,  yet  we  are  at  liberty  to 
conceive  that  the  players  agree  to  have  four  trials,  because,  even  if 
the  game  be  decided  in  fewer  than  four  trials,  no  difference  will  be 


14j  pascal  and  fermat. 

made  in  the  decision  by  the  superfluous  trial  or  trials.     Pascal 
j)uts  this  point  very  clearly. 

In  the  context  of  the  first  passage  quoted  from  Leibnitz  in 
Art.  15,  he  refers  to  "  les  belles  pensees  de  Alea,  de  Messieurs 
Fermat,  Pascal  et  Huygens,  oil  Mr.  Roberval  ne  pouvoit  ou  ne 
vouloit  rien  comprendre." 

The  difficulty  raised  by  Roberval  was  in  effect  reproduced  by 
D'Alembert,  as  we  shall  see  hereafter. 

18.  Pascal  then  proceeds  to  apply  Format's  method  to  an 
example  in  which  there  are  three  players.  Suppose  that  the  first 
player  wants  one  point,  and  each  of  the  other  players  two  points. 
The  game  will  then  be  certainly  decided  in  the  course  of  three 
trials.  Take  the  letters  a,  h,  c  and  write  down  all  the  combinations 
which  can  be  formed  of  three  letters.  These  combinations  are  the 
following,  27  in  number: 


a 

a 

a 

h 

a 

a 

C 

a 

a 

a 

a 

h 

h 

a 

b 

c 

a 

b 

a 

a 

c 

h 

a 

c 

c 

a 

c 

a 

h 

a 

b 

b 

a 

c 

b 

a 

a 

h 

h 

b 

b 

b 

c 

b 

b 

a 

h 

c 

b 

b 

c 

c 

b 

c 

a 

c 

a 

b 

c 

a 

c 

c 

a 

a 

c 

b 

b 

c 

b 

c 

c 

b 

a 

c 

c 

b 

c 

G 

c 

c 

c 

Let  A  denote  the  player  who  wants  one  point,  and  B  and  C  the 
other  two  players.  By  examining  the  27  cases,  Pascal  finds  13 
Avhich  are  exclusively  favourable  to  A,  namely,  those  in  which  a 
occurs  twice  or  oftener,  and  those  in  which  a,  b,  and  c  each  occur 
once.  He  finds  3  cases  which  he  considers  equally  favourable  to 
A  and  B,  namely,  those  in  which  a  occurs  once  and  b  twice ;  and 
similarly  he  finds  3  cases  equally  favourable  to  A  and  C.  On  the 
whole  then  the  number  of  cases  favourable  to  A  may  be  considered 
to  be  13  +  f  +  f,  that  is  16.  Then  Pascal  finds  4  cases  which 
are  exclusively  favourable  to  B,  namely  those  represented  by  bbb, 
ebb,   bcb,  and  bbc ;   and  thus  on  the  whole  the  number  of  cases 


PASCAL   AND    FERMAT.  15 

favourable  to  B  may  be  considered  to  be  4  +  |,  that  is  5^.  Simi- 
larly the  number  of  cases  favourable  to  C  may  be  considered  to 
be  5^.  Thus  it  would  appear  that  the  chances  oi  A,  B,  and  C  are 
respectively  as  16,  5i,  and  51 

Pascal,  however,  says  that  by  his  own  method  he  had  found 
that  the  chances  are  as  17,  5,  and  5.  He  infers  that  the  differ- 
ence arises  from  the  circumstance  that  in  Fermat's  method  it  is 
assumed  that  three  trials  will  necessarily  be  made,  which  is  not 
assumed  in  his  own  method.  Pascal  was  wrong  in  supposing  that 
the  true  result  could  be  affected  by  assuming  that  three  trials 
w^ould  necessarily  be  made ;  and  indeed,  as  we  have  seen,  in  the 
case  of  two  players,  Pascal  himself  had  correctly  maintained 
against  Roberval  that  a  similar  assumption  was  legitimate. 

19.  A  letter  from  Pascal  to  Format  is  dated  August  29th,  1654. 
Format  refers  to  the  Problem  of  Points  for  the  case  of  three 
players;  he  says  that  the  proportions  17,  5,  and  5  are  correct  for 
the  example  which  we  have  just  considered.  This  letter,  how- 
ever, does  not  seem  to  be  the  reply  to  Pascal's  of  August  24th,  but 
to  an  earlier  letter  which  has  not  been  preserved. 

On  the  25th  of  September  Format  writes  a  letter  to  Pascal, 
in  which  Pascal's  error  is  pointed  out.  Pascal  had  supposed 
that  such  a  combination  as  ace  represented  a  case  equally  favour- 
able to  A  and  C\  but,  as  Format  says,  this  case  is  exclusively 
favourable  to  A,  because  here  A  gains  one  point  before  C  gains 
one  ;  and  as  A  only  wanted  one  point  the  game  is  thus  decided 
in  his  favour.  When  the  necessary  correction  is  made,  the  result 
is,  that  the  chances  of  A,  B,  and  C  are  as  17,  5,  and  5,  as  Pascal 
had  found  by  his  own  method. 

Fermat  then  gives  another  solution,  for  the  sake  of  Roberval, 
in  which  he  does  not  assume  that  three  trials  will  necessarilv  be 
made;  and  he  arrives  at  the  same  result  as  before. 

In  the  remainder  of  his  letter  Fermat  enunciates  some  of  his 
memorable  propositions  relating  to  the  Theory  of  Numbers. 

Pascal  replied  on  October  27th,  1654,  to  Fermat's  letter,  and 
said  that  he  was  entirelv  satisfied. 


16  PASCAL   AND    FERMAT. 

20.  There  is  another  letter  £i'oni  Fermat  to  Pascal  which  is 
not  dated.  It  relates  to  a  simple  question  which  Pascal  had  pro- 
posed to  Fermat.  A  person  undertakes  to  throw  a  six  with  a  die 
in  eight  throws  ;  supposing  him  to  have  made  three  throws  with- 
out success,  what  portion  of  the  stake  should  he  be  allowed  to  take 
on  condition  of  giving  up  his  fourth  throw  ?  The  chance  of  success 
is  J,  so  that  he  should  be  allowed  to  take  J  of  the  stake  on  con- 
dition of  giving  up  his  throw.  But  suppose  that  we  wish  to  esti- 
mate the  value  of  the  fourth  throw  before  any  throw  is  made.  The 
first  throw  is  worth  J  of  the  stake ;  the  second  is  worth  J  of  what 
remains,  that  is  -^  of  the  stake  ;  the  third  throw  is  worth  i  of  w^hat 
now  remains,  that  is  -ff^  of  the  stake  ;  the  fourth  throw  is  worth 
J  of  what  now  remains,  that  is  -^-ff-Q  of  the  stake. 

It  seems  possible  from  Format's  letter  that  Pascal  had  not  dis- 
tinguished between  the  two  cases  ;  but  Pascal's  letter,  to  which 
Format's  is  a  reply,  has  not  been  preserved,  so  that  we  cannot 
be  certain  on  the  point. 

21.  We  see  then  that  the  Problem  of  Points  was  the  prin- 
cipal question  discussed  by  Pascal  and  Fermat,  and  it  was  certainly 
not  exhausted  by  them.  For  they  confined  themselves  to  the  case 
in  which  the  players  are  supposed  to  possess  equal  skill;  and  their 
methods  would  have  been  extremely  laborious  if  applied  to  any 
examples  except  those  of  the  most  simple  kind.  Pascal's  method 
seems  the  more  refined ;  the  student  will  perceive  that  it  depends 
on  the  same  principles  as  the  modern  solution  of  the  problem 
by  the  aid  of  the  Calculus  of  Finite  Differences ;  see  Laplace, 
Theorie...cles  Proh.  page  210. 

Gouraud  awards  to  Format's  treatment  of  the  problem  an 
amount  of  praise  which  seems  excessive,  whether  we  consider  that 
treatment  absolutely  or  relatively  in  comparison  with  Pascal's  ;  see 
his  page  9, 

22.  We  have  next  to  consider  Pascal's  Traite  du  triangle 
arithmetique.  This  treatise  was  printed  about  1G5-4,  but  not 
pubhshed  until  1665  ;  see  Montucla,  p.  387.  The  treatise  will  be 
found  in  the  fifth  volume  of  the  edition  of  Pascal's  works  to  which 
we  have  already  referred. 


PASCAL   AND    FERMAT.  17 

The  Arithmetical  Triangle  in  its  simplest  form  consists  of  the 


following 

table : 

1         1 

1 

1 

1 

1 

1 

1 

2        3 

4 

0 

6 

7 

8 

9 

3         G 

10 

15 

21 

28 

30  ... 

4       10 

20 

35 

dQ 

8-i.. 

t 

5       15 

35 

70 

120.. 

• 

6       21 

50 

120. 

■  • 

7      28 

81^. 

•  • 

8       3G.. 

• 

%J     a   •  • 

J.    • 

•  • 

In  the  successive  horizontal  rows  we  have  what  are  now  called 
the  figurate  numbers.  Pascal  distinguishes  them  into  orders.  He 
calls  the  simple  units  1,  1,  1,  1,...  which  form  the  first  row,  num- 
bers of  the  first  order;  he  calls  the  numbers  1,  2,  3,  4,...  which 
form  the  second  row,  numbers  of  the  second  order;  and  so  on. 
The  numbers  of  the  third  order  1,  3,  0,  10,...  had  already  received 
the  name  oi  triangular  numbers;  and  the  numbers  of  the  fourth 
order  1,  4,  10,  20,...  the  name  oi pyr^amidal  numbers.  Pascal  says 
that  the  numbers  of  the  fifth  order  1,  5,  15,  35,...  had  not  yet 
received  an  express  name,  and  he  proposes  to  call  them  triangulo- 
triangulaires. 

In  modern  notation  the  if^  term  of  the  r*^  order  is 

n(ii  +  l)  ...  {n  +  r -  2) 


r-1 


Pascal  constructs  the  Arithmetical  Triangle  by  the  foUowdng 
definition  ;  each  number  is  the  sum  of  that  immediately  above  it 
and  that  immediately  to  the  left  of  it.     Thus 

10  =  4  +  0,        35  =  20  +  15,       126  =  70  +  50,... 

The  properties  of  the  numbers  are  developed  by  Pascal  with 
great  skill  and  distinctness.  For  example,  suppose  we  require  the 
sum  of  the  first  n  terms  of  the  r^^  order  :  the  sum  is  equal  to  the 
number  of  the  combinations  of  n  +  r  —  1  things  taken  r  at  a 
time,  and  Pascal  establishes  this  by  an  inductive  proof 

2 


18  PASCAL  AND   FERMAT. 

23.  Pascal  applies  liis  Arithmetical  Triangle  to  various  subjects ; 
among  tliese  we  have  the  Problem  of  Points,  the  Theory  of  Com- 
binations, and  the  Powers  of  Binomial  Quantities.  We  are  here 
only  concerned  with  the  application  to  the  first  subject. 

In  the  Arithmetical  T^^iangle  a  line  drawn  so  as  to  cut  off 
an  equal  number  of  units  from  the  top  horizontal  row  and  the 
extreme  left-hand  vertical  column  is  called  a  base. 

The  bases  are  numbered,  beginning  from  the  top  left-hand 
corner.  Thus  the  tenth  base  is  a  line  drawn  through  the  num- 
bers 1,  9,  36,  84,  12G,  12G,  84,  36,  9,  1.  It  will  be  perceived  that 
the  r*^  base  contains  r  numbers. 

Suppose  then  that  A  wants  m  points  and  that  B  wants  n 
points.  Take  the  {m  +  ii)^^  base;  the  chance  oi  A  is  to  the  chance 
of  B  as  the  sum  of  the  first  n  numbers  of  the  base,  beginning  at 
the  highest  row,  is  to  the  sum  of  the  last  m  numbers.  Pascal 
establishes  this  by  induction. 

Pascal's  result  may  be  easily  she^vn  to  coincide  with  that 
obtained  by  other  methods.  For  the  terms  in  the  (m  +  ti)"^  base 
are  the  coefficients  in  the  expansion  of  (1  -f  xY'^''~^  by  the  Binomial 
Theorem.  Let  m  +  n  —  l=r\  then  Pascal's  result  amounts  to 
saying  that  the  chance  of  A  is  proportional  to 

-  r  (r  —  1)  r  (r  —  l)  ...  (r  —  n-\-2) 

I  .  z  n  —  1 


and  the  chance   of  B  proportional  to 

Ij^yj^  r  (r-1)  ^  ^^^^   ^   r{r-l)...{r-m  +  2) 


1.2      ^^1-1 


This  agrees   with   the   result   now  usually   given   in  elementary 
treatises;  see  Algebra,  Chapter  Liii. 

24.  Pascal  then  notices  some  particular  examples.  (1)  Sup- 
pose that  A  wants  one  point  and  B  wants  n  points.  (2)  Suppose 
that  A  wants  n  —  1  points  and  B  wants  n  points.  (3)  Suppose 
that  A  wants  n—  2  points  and  B  wants  n  points.  An  interesting 
relation  holds  between  the  second  and  third  examples,  which  we 
will  exhibit. 


PASCAL   AXD    FERMAT.  19 

Let  M  denote  the  number  of  cases  which  are  favourable  to  A , 
and  N  the  number  of  cases  which  are  favourable  to  B,  Let 
r  =  2/1  -  2. 

In  the  second  example  we  have 

M  —  N.=  . -^ =  X  say. 

\n—  1    I  ;2  —  1  "^ 

Then  if  2  aS'  denote  the  whole  sum  at  stake,  A  is  entitled  to 
-^  .  — ^—  ,  that  is  to  —  (2*'  +X)\  so  that  he  may  be  considered 
to  have  recovered  his  own  stake  and  to  have  won  the  fraction 
^7  of  his  adversary's  stake. 

In  the  third  example  we  have 
il/  +  lY  =  T-\ 

2   r  -  1  2  (?2  -  1)  1  r  -  1      1\{n-\\ 


n  —  \    ?i—  2         \n  —  1    In  —  1 


Thus  we  shall  find  that  A  may  be  considered  to  have  recovered 
his  own  stake,  and  to  have  won  the  fraction  ■— j  of  his  adversary's 

stake. 

Hence,  comparing  the  second  and  third  examples,  we  see  that  if 
the  player  who  wins  the  first  point  also  wins  the  second  point, 
his  advantage  when  he  has  gained  the  second  point  is  double  what 
it  was  when  he  had  gained  the  first  point,  whatever  may  be  the 
number  of  points  in  the  game, 

25.  We  have  now  analysed  all  that  has  been  preser\'ed  of 
Pascal's  researches  on  our  subject.  It  seems  however  that  he  had 
intended  to  collect  these  researches  into  a  complete  treatise.  A 
letter  is  extant  addressed  by  him  Celeberrimce  Matheseos  Academice 
Parisiensi ;  this  Academy  was  one  of  those  voluntary  associations 
which  preceded  the  formation  of  formal  scientific  societies  :  see 
Pascal's  Works,  Vol.  iv.  p.  356.  In  the  letter  Pascal  enumerates 
various  treatises  which  he  had  prepared  and  which  he  hoped  to 


20  PASCAL  AND   FERMAT. 

publish,  among  wliicli  was  to  be  one  on  chances.  His  language 
shews  that  he  had  a  high  opinion  of  the  novelty  and  importance 
of  the  matter  he  proposed  to  discuss ;  he  says, 

Novissima  autem  ac  penitus  intentatse  materise  tractatio,  scilicet  de 
compositione  alece  in  hid  is  ijysi  subjeclis,  qnod  gallico  nostro  idiomate 
dicitur  (/aire  les  ^;ar^is  cles  jeux) :  ubi  ancej)s  fortuna  sequitate  rationis 
ita  reprimitur  ut  utrique  lusorum  quod  jure  competit  exacte  semper 
assignetur.  Quod  quidem  eo  fortius  ratiocinando  quserendnm,  quo 
minus  tentando  investigari  possit :  ambigiii  enim  sortis  eventus  fortiiitse 
contingentise  potius  quam  nattirali  necessitati  meritb  tribuuntur.  Ideo 
res  hactenus  erravit  incerta ;  nunc  autem  qu?e  experimento  rebellis 
fuerat,  rationis  dominium  effugere  non  potuit :  eam  quippe  tanta  se- 
curitate  in  artem  per  geometriam  reduximus,  ut  certitudinis  ejus 
j^articeps  facta,  jam  audacter  prodeat ;  et  sic  matheseos  demonstrationes 
cum  alese  incertitudine  jungendo,  et  qu?e  contraria  videntur  conciliando, 
ab  utraque  nominationem  suam  accipiens  stupendum  hunc  titulum  jure 
sibi  arrogat :  alece  geometria. 

But  the  design  was  probably  never  accomplished.  The  letter 
is  dated  1651;  Pascal  died  in  1662,  at  the  early  age  of  39. 

26.  Neglecting  the  trifling  hints  which  may  be  found  in  pre- 
ceding writers  we  may  say  that  the  Theory  of  Probability  really 
commenced  with  Pascal  and  Format ;  and  it  would  be  difficult  to 
find  two  names  which  could  confer  higher  honour  on  the  subject. 

The  fame  of  Pascal  rests  on  an  extensive  basis,  of  which 
mathematical  and  physical  science  form  only  a  part ;  and  the 
regret  which  we  may  feel  at  his  renunciation  of  the  studies  in 
which  he  gained  his  earliest  renown  may  be  diminished  by  reflect- 
ing on  his  memorable  Letters,  or  may  be  lost  in  deeper  sorrow 
wdien  we  contemplate  the  fragments  which  alone  remain  of  the 
great  work  on  the  evidences  of  religion  that  was  to  have  engaged 
the  efforts  of  his  maturest  powers. 

The  fame  of  Format  is  confined  to  a  narrower  range ;  but  it  is 
of  a  special  kind  which  is  without  a  parallel  in  the  history  of 
science.  Format  enunciated  various  remarkable  propositions  in 
the  theory  of  numbers.  Two  of  these  are  more  important  than 
the  rest;  one  of  them  after  bafiling  the  powers  of  Euler  and  La- 
grange finally  yielded  to  Cauchy,  and  tlie  other  remains  still  un- 


PASCAL   AND   FEEMAT.  21 

conquered.  The  interest  which  attaches  to  the  propositions  is 
increased  by  the  uncertainty  which  subsists  as  to  whether  Fermat 
himself  had  succeeded  in  demonstrating  them. 

The  French  government  in  the  time  of  Louis  Philippe  assigned 
a  grant  of  money  for  publishing  a  new  edition  of  Format's  works  ; 
but  unfortunately  the  design  has  never  been  accomplished.  The 
edition  which  we  have  quoted  in  Art.  11  has  been  reprinted  in 
facsimile  by  Friedlander  at  Berlin  in  1861. 

27.  At  the  time  when  the  Theory  of  Probability  started  from 
the  hands  of  Pascal  and  Fermat,  they  were  the  most  distinguished 
mathematicians  of  Europe.  Descartes  died  in  1650,  and  Newton 
and  Leibnitz  were  as  yet  unknown  ;  Newton  was  born  in  1642, 
and  Leibnitz  in  1646.  Huygens  was  born  in  1629,  and  had 
already  given  specimens  of  his  powers  and  tokens  of  his  future 
eminence;  but  at  this  epoch  he  could  not  have  been  placed  on  the 
level  of  Pascal  and  Fermat.  In  England  Wall  is,  born  in  1616, 
and  appointed  Savilian  j^rofessor  of  geometry  at  Oxford  in  1649, 
was  steadily  rising  in  reputation,  while  Barrow,  born  in  1630,  was 
not  appointed  Lucasian  professor  of  mathematics  at  Cambridge 
until  1663. 

It  might  have  been  anticipated  that  a  subject  interesting  in. 
itself  and  discussed  by  the  two  most  distinguished  mathematicians 
of  the  time  would  have  attracted  rapid  and  general  attention ;  but 
such  does  not  appear  to  have  been  the  case.  The  two  great  men 
themselves  seem  to  have  been  indifferent  to  any  extensive  publi- 
cation of  their  investigations;  it  was  sufficient  for  each  to  gain 
the  approbation  of  the  other.  Pascal  finally  withdrew  from  science 
and  the  world ;  Fermat  devoted  to  mathematics  only  the  leisure  of 
a  laborious  life,  and  died  in  1665. 

The  invention  of  the  Differential  Calculus  by  Newton  and 
Leibnitz  soon  offered  to  mathematicians  a  subject  of  absorbing 
interest ;  and  we  shall  find  that  the  Theory  of  Probability  advanced 
but  little  during  the  half  century  which  followed  the  date  of  the 
correspondence  between  Pascal  and  Fermat. 


CHAPTER    III. 

HUYGENS. 

28.  We  have  now  to  speak  of  a  treatise  by  Hu3^gens  entitled 
Be  Ratiociniis  in  Ludo  Alece.  This  treatise  was  first  printed  by 
Schooten  at  the  end  of  his  work  entitled  Francisci  a  Bcliooten 
Exercitationum  Mathematicarum  Lihri  quinque ;  it  occupies  pages 
519... 534  of  the  volume.  The  date  1658  is  assigned  to  Schooten's 
work  by  Montucla,  but  the  only  copy  which  I  have  seen  is  dated 
1657. 

Schooten  had  been  the  instructor  of  Huygens  in  mathematics ; 
and  the  treatise  which  we  have  to  examine  was  communicated  by 
Huygens  to  Schooten  w^ritten  in  their  vernacular  tongue,  and 
Schooten  translated  it  into  Latin. 

It  appears  from  a  letter  written  by  Schooten  to  Wallis,  that 
Wallis  had  seen  and  commended  Huygens's  treatise  ;  see  Wallis's 
Algebra,  1693,  p.  833. 

Leibnitz  commends  it.  Leibnitii  Opera  Omnia,  ed.  Dutens, 
Vol.  VI.  part  1,  p.  318. 

29.  In  his  letter  to  Schooten  which  is  printed  at  the  beginning 
of  the  treatise  Huygens  refers  to  his  predecessors  in  these  words : 
Sciendum  verb,  quod  jam  pridem  inter  prsestantissimos  totd 
Gallia  Geometras  calculus  hie  agitatus  fuerit,  ne  quis  indebitam 
mihi  primse  inventionis  gloriam  hac  in  re  tribuat.  Huygens  ex- 
presses a  very  high  opinion  of  the  importance  and  interest  of  the 
subject  he  was  bringing  under  the  notice  of  mathematicians. 

30.  The  treatise  is  reprinted  with  a  commentary  in  James 
Bernoulli's  Ars  Conjectandi,  and  forms  the  first  of  the  four  parts 


huvgp:ns.  2.3 

of  which  that  work  is  composed.  Two  English  translations  of  the 
treatise  have  been  published  ;  one  which  has  been  attributed  to 
Motte,  but  which  was  probably  by  Arbuthnot,  and  the  other  by 
W.  Browne. 

31.  The  treatise  contains  fourteen  propositions.  The  first  pro- 
position asserts  that  if  a  player  has  equal  chances  of  gaining  a  sum 
represented  by  a  or  a  sum  represented  by  b,  his  expectation  is 
^  (a  +  b).  The  second  proposition  asserts  that  if  a  player  has  equal 
chances  of  gaining  a  or  6  or  c,  his  expectation  is  J  (a  +  6  +  c).  The 
third  proposition  asserts  that  if  a  player  has  2^  chances  of  gaining  a 

and  q  chances  of  gaining  b,  his  expectation  is —  . 

i^  +  2' 

It  has  been   stated   with  reference   to   the   last  proposition  : 

*'  Elementary  as  this  truth  may  now  appear,  it  was  not  received 

altogether  without  opposition."     Lubbock  and  Drinhwater,  p.  42. 

It  is  not  obvious  to  what  these  words  refer;   for  there  does  not 

appear  to  have  been  any  opposition  to  the  elementary  principle, 

except  at  a  much  later  period  by  D'Alembert. 

82.  The  fourth,  fifth,  sixth,  and  seventh  propositions  discuss 
simple  cases  of  the  Problem  of  Points,  when  there  are  two  players ; 
the  method  is  similar  to  Pascal's,  see  Art.  12.  The  eiirhth  and 
ninth  propositions  discuss  simple  cases  of  the  Problem  of  Points 
when  there  are  ^/i?'e^  players  ;  the  method  is  similar  to  that  for  two 
players. 

83.  Huygens  now  proceeds  to  some  questions  relating  to  dice. 
In  his  tenth  proposition  he  investigates  in  how  many  throws  a 
player  may  undertake  to  throw  a  six  with  a  single  die.  In  his 
eleventh  proposition  he  investigates  in  how  many  throws  a  player 
may  undertake  to  throw  twelve  with  a  pair  of  dice.  In  his 
twelfth  proposition  he  investigates  how  many  dice  a  player  must 
have  in  order  to  undertake  that  in  one  throw  two  sixes  at  least 
may  appear.  The  thirteenth  proposition  consists  of  the  following 
problem.  A  and  B  play  with  two  dice ;  if  a  seven  is  thrown, 
^1  wins;  if  a  ten  is  thrown,  B  Avins;  if  any  other  number  is 
thrown,  the  stakes  are  divided :  compare  the  chances  of  A  and  B. 
They  are  shewn  to  be  as  13  is  to  11. 


24  ^  HUYGENS. 

84.  The  fourteenth  proposition  consists  of  the  following 
problem.  A  and  B  play  with  two  dice  on  the  condition  that  A 
is  to  have  the  stake  if  he  throws  six  before  B  throws  seven,  and 
that  B  is  to  have  the  stake  if  he  throws  seven  before  A  throws 
six ;  ^  is  to  begin,  and  they  are  to  throw  alternately ;  compare 
the  chances  of  A  and  B. 

We  will  give  the  solution  of  Huygens.  Let  B's  chance  be 
worth  X,  and  the  stake  a,  so  that  a  —  a?  is  the  worth  of  ^'s  chance  ; 
then  whenever  it  is  ^.'s  turn  to  throw  x  will  express  the  value 
of  B's  chance,  but  when  it  is  i>'s  own  turn  to  throw  his  chance 
will  have  a  different  value,  say  ?/.  Suppose  then  A  is  about  to 
throw ;  there  are  36  equally  likely  cases ;  in  5  cases  A  wins  and  B 
takes  nothing,  in  the  other  81  cases  A  loses  and  B's  turn  comes 
on,  which  is  worth  y  by  supposition.  So  that  by  the  third  propo- 
sition of  the  treatise  the  expectation  of  B  is ^ — -  ,  that  is, 

^2l,     Thus 
So  81?/ 

Now  suppose  B  about  to  throw,  and  let  us  estimate  ^'s  chance. 
There  are  S6  equally  likely  cases  ;  in  6  cases  B  wins  and  A  takes 
nothing ;  in  the  other  80  cases  B  loses  and  ^'s  turn  comes  on 
again,  in  which  case  B's  chance  is  worth  x  by  supposition.    So 

that  the  expectation  of  B  is  — ^j^ —  .     Thus 

(ja-^SOx 

81« 

From  these  equations  it  will  be  found  that  x  =  -^  ,    and   thus 

80cj 


a  —  x=^ 


61 


,  so  that  ^'s  chance  is  to  ^'s  chance  as  80  is  to  81. 


85.  At  the  end  of  his  treatise  Huygens  gives  five  problems 
without  analysis  or  demonstration,  which  he  leaves  to  the  reader. 
Solutions  are  given  by  Bernoulli  in  the  Ars  Conjectandi.  The 
following  are  the  problems. 

(1)  A  and  B  play  with  two  dice  on  this  condition,  that  A  gains 
if  he  throws  six,  and  B  gains  if  he  throws  seven.     A  first  has  one 


HUYGENS.  25 

throw,  then  B  has  two  throAvs,  then  A  two  throws,  and  so  on  until 
one  or  the  other  gains.  Shew  that  ^'s  chance  is  to  J5's  as  10355  to 
12276. 

(2)  Three  players  A,  B,  C  take  twelve  balls,  eight  of  which 
are  black  and  four  white.  They  play  on  the  following  condition  ; 
they  are  to  draw  blindfold,  and  the  first  who  draws  a  white  ball 
wins.  A  is  to  have  the  first  turn,  B  the  next,  G  the  next,  then 
A  again,  and  so  on.     Determine  the  chances  of  the  players. 

Bernoulli  solves  this  on  three  suppositions  as  to  the  meaning  ; 
first  he  supposes  that  each  ball  is  replaced  after  it  is  drawn  ; 
secondly  he  supposes  that  there  is  only  one  set  of  twelve  balls, 
and  that  the  balls  are  not  replaced  after  being  drawn  ;  thirdly  he 
supposes  that  each  player  has  his  own  set  of  twelve  balls,  and  that 
the  balls  are  not  replaced  after  being  drawn. 

(3)  There  are  forty  cards  forming  four  sets  each  of  ten  cards ; 
A  plays  with  B  and  undertakes  in  drawing  four  cards  to  obtain 
one  of  each  set.    Shew  that  ^'s  chance  is  to  -S's  as  1000  is  to  8139. 

(4)  Twelve  balls  are  taken,  eight  of  which  are  black  and  four 
are  white.  A  pla3^s  with  B  and  undertakes  in  drawing  seven  balls 
blindfold  to  obtain  three  white  balls.  Compare  the  chances  of 
A  and  B. 

(5)  A  and  B  take  each  twelve  counters  and  play  with  three 
dice  on  this  condition,  that  if  eleven  is  throAA-n  A  gives  a  counter 
to  B,  and  if  fourteen  is  thrown  B  gives  a  counter  to  A  ;  and  he 
wins  the  game  who  first  obtains  all  the  counters.  Shew  that  A 's 
chance  is  to  ^'s  as  244140625  is  to  282429536481. 

oQ>.  The  treatise  by  Huygens  continued  to  form  the  best 
account  of  the  subject  until  it  was  superseded  by  the  more  elabo- 
rate works  of  James  Bernoulli,  Montmort,  and  De  Moivre.  Before 
we  speak  of  these  we  shall  give  some  account  of  the  history  of  the 
theory  of  combinations,  and  of  the  inquiries  into  the  laws  of 
mortality  and  the  principles  of  life  insurance,  and  notices  of 
various  miscellaneous  investigations. 


CHAPTER    IV. 


ON  COMBIjSTATIONS. 

87.  The  theory  of  combinations  is  closely  connected  witli  the 
theory  of  probability ;  so  that  we  shall  find  it  convenient  to  imi- 
tate Montucla  in  giving  some  account  of  the  writings  on  the 
former  subject  up  to  the  close  of  the  seventeenth  century. 

88.  The  earliest  notice  we  have  found  respecting  combinations 
is  contained  in  Wallis's  Algebra  as  quoted  by  him  from  a  work  by 
William  Buckley;  see  Wallis's  Algebra  1693,  page  489.  Buckley 
was  a  member  of  King's  College,  Cambridge,  and  lived  in  the  time 
of  Edward  the  Sixth.  He  wrote  a  small  tract  in  Latin  verse  con- 
taining the  rules  of  Arithmetic.  In .  Sir  John  Leslie's  Pliilosophj 
of  Arithmetic  full  citations  are  given  from  Buckley's  work;  in 
Dr.  Peacock's  History  of  A  rithmetic  a  citation  is  given ;  see  also 
De  Morgan's  Arithmetical  Books  from  the  invention  of  Printing .. . 

Wallis  quotes  twelve  lines  which  form  a  Regula  Comhinationis, 
and  then  explains  them.  We  may  say  briefly  that  the  rule 
amounts  to  assigning  the  whole  number  of  combinations  which  can 
be  formed  of  a  given  number  of  things,  when  taken  one  at  a  time, 
or  two  at  a  time,  or  three  at  a  time,. . .  and  so  on  until  they  are  taken 
all  together.  The  rule  shews  that  the  mode  of  proceeding  was 
the  same  as  that  which  we  shall  indicate  hereafter  in  speaking 
of  Schooten  ;  thus  for  four  things  Buckley's  rule  gives,  like  Schoo- 
ten's,  1  +  2  +  4  +  8,  that  is  15  combinations  in  all. 

By  some  mistake  or  misprint  Wallis  apparently  overestimates 
the  age  of  Buckley's  work,  when  he  says  *' . . .  in  Arithmetica  sua, 


lUUHUsius.  27 

versibus  scripta  ante  annos  plus  minus  190;"  in  the  ninth  Chapter 
of  the  Algebra  the  date  of  about  1550  is  assigned  to  Buckley's 
death. 

89.  We  must  now  notice  an  example  of  combinations  which 
is  of  historical  notoriety  although  it  is  very  slightly  connected 
with   the  theory. 

A  book  was  published  at  Antwerp  in  1617  by  Erycius  Pu- 
teanus  under  the  title,  Erycii  Puteani  Fietatis  TJiaumata  in 
Bernardi  Bauhusii  ^  Societate  Jesu  Proteum  Parthenium.  The 
book  consists  of  IIG  quarto  pages,  exclusive  of  seven  pages,  not 
numbered,  which  contain  an  Index,  Censura,  Summa  Privilegii, 
and  a  typographical  ornament. 

It  appears  that  Bernardus  Bauhusius  composed  the  following 
line  in  honour  of  the  Virgin  Mary : 

Tot  tibi  sunt  dotes,   Virgo,   quot  sidera  copIo. 

This  verse  is  arranged  in  1022  different  ways,  occupying  48  pages 
of  the  work.  First  we  have  54  arrangements  commencing  Tot  tibi; 
then  25  arrangements  commencing  Tot  sunt;  and  so  on.  Although 
these  arrangements  are  sometimes  ascribed  to  Puteanus,  they  ajD- 
pear  from  the  dedication  of  the  book  to  be  the  work  of  Bauhusius 
himself;  Puteanus  supplies  verses  of  his  own  and  a  series  of  chap- 
ters in  prose  which  he  calls  Thaumata,  and  which  are  distinguished 
by  the  Greek  letters  from  A  to  O  inclusive.  The  number  1022  is 
the  same  as  the  number  of  the  stars  accordino-  to  Ptolemy's  Cata- 
logue,  wdiich  coincidence  Puteanus  seems  to  consider  the  great 
merit  of  the  labours  of  Bauhusius  ;  see  his  page  82. 

It  is  to  be  observed  that  Bauhusius  did  not  profess  to  include 
all  the  possible  arrangements  of  his  line;  he  expressly  rejected  those 
which  would  have  conveyed  a  sense  inconsistent  with  the  glory  of 
the  Virgin  Mary.     As  Puteanus  sa3\s,  page   103, 
Dicere  horruit  Vates : 

Sidera   tot   ca?lo,    Virgo,  quot  sunt  tibi   Dotes, 

imb  in  hunc  sensum  producere  Proteum  recusavit,  ne  laudem  immi- 
nueret.    Sic  igitur  contraxit  versuum  numerum ;  ut  Dotium  augeret. 

40.  The  line  due  to  Bauhusius  on  account  of  its  numerous 
an-angements  seems  to  have  attracted  gi'eat  attention  during  the 
following  century  ;  the  discussion  on  the  subject  was  finally  settled 


28  PASCAL. 

by  James  Bernoulli  in  his  Ars  Coiijectandi,  where  he  thus  details 
the  history  of  the  problem. 

. , .  Quemadmodum  cernere  est  in  hexametro  a  Bernli.  Bauhusio  Jesuita 
Lovaniensi  in  laudem  Virginis  Deiparse  constructo  : 

Tot  tihi  sunt  Dotes,  Virgo,  quot  sidera  ccdo ; 
qiiem  dignnm  peculiari  opera  duxerunt  plures  Viri  celebres.  Erycius 
Puteanus  in  libello,  quern.  Tliaumata  Pietatis  inscripsit,  variationes  ejus 
utiles  integris  48  paginis  enumerat,  easque  numero  stellarum,  quarum 
vulgb  1022  recensentur,  accommodat,  omissis  scrupulosius  illis,  quse  di- 
cere  videntur,  tot  sidera  cselo  esse,  quot  Marine  dotes;  nam  Mariae 
dotes  esse  multo  plures.  Eundem  numerum  1022  ex  Puteano  repetifc 
Gerh.  Yossius,  cap.  7,  de  Scient.  Matliemat.  Prestetus  Gallus  in  prima 
editione  Element.  Matliemat.  pag.  358.  Proteo  huic  2196  variationes 
attribuit,  sed  facta  revisione  in  altera  edit.  torn.  pr.  pag.  133.  numerum 
earum  dimidio  fere  auctum  ad  3276  extendit.  Industrii  Actorum  Lips. 
Collectores  m.  Jun.  1686,  in  recensione  Tractatus  Wallisiani  de  Algebra, 
numerum  in  qusestione  (quem  Auctor  ipse  definire  non  fuit  ausus)  ad 
2580  determinant.  Et  ipse  postmodum  Wallisius  in  edit,  latina  operis 
sui  Oxon.  anno  1693.  impressa,  pagin.  494.  eundem  ad  3096  profert. 
Sed  omnes  adliuc  a  vero  deficientes,  ut  delusam  tot  Yirorum  post 
adhibitas  quoque  secundas  curas  in  re  levi  perspicaciam  meritb  mireris. 
Ars  Conjectandi,  page  78. 

James  Bernoulli  seems  to  imply  that  the  two  editions  of 
Wallis's  Algebra  differ  in  their  enumeration  of  the  arrangements 
of  the  line  due  to  Bauhusius ;  but  this  is  not  the  case :  the  two 
editions  agree  in  investigation  and  in  result. 

James  Bernoulli  proceeds  to  say  that  he  had  found  that  there 
could  be  3312  arrangements  without  breaking  the  law  of  metre; 
this  excludes  spondaic  lines  but  includes  those  which  have  no 
caesura.     The  analysis  which  produces  this  number  is  given. 

41.  The  earliest  treatise  on  combinations  which  we  have  ob- 
served is  due  to  Pascal.  It  is  contained  in  the  work  on  the 
Arithmetical  Triangle  which  we  have  noticed  in  Art.  22;  it  will 
also  be  found  in  the  fifth  volume  of  Pascal's  works,  Paris  1819, 
pages  86—107. 

The  investigations  of  Pascal  on  combinations  depend  on  his 
Arithmetical  Triangle.  The  following  is  his  principal  result;  we 
express  it  in  modern  notation. 


PASCAL.  29 

Take  an  Arithmetical  Triangle  with  r  numbers  in  its  base; 
then  the  sum  of  the  numbers  in  the  _29"'  horizontal  row  is  equal  to 
the  multitude  of  the  combinations  of  r  things  taken  p  at  a  time. 
For  example,  in  Art  22  we  have  a  triangle  with  10  numbers  in 
its  base ;  now  take  the  numbers  in  the  8th  horizontal  column  ; 
their  sum  is  1  4-8  +  36,  that  is  45;  and  there  are  45  combinations 
of  10  things  taken  8  at  a  time.  Pascal's  proof  is  inductive.  It 
may  be  observed  that  multitudo  is  Pascal's  word  in  tlie  Latin  of 
his  treatise,  and  multitude  in  the  French  version  of  a  part  of  the 
treatise  which  is  given  in  pages  22 — 30  of  the  volume. 

From  this  he  deduces  various  inferences  such  as  the  followino-. 
Let  there  be  n  things ;  the  sum  of  the  multitude  of  the  combinations 
which  can  be  formed,  one  at  a  time,  two  at  a  time,...  ,  up  to  n  at 
a  time,  is  2''—  1. 

At  the  end  Pascal  considers  this  problem.  Datis  duobus  numeris 
inaequalibus,  invenire  quot  modis  minor  in  majore  combinetur. 
And  from  his  Arithmetical  THangle  he  deduces  in  effect  the  follow- 
ing result ;  the  number  of  combinations  of  r  things  taken  p  at 
a  time  is 

(^+1)  (p  +  2)  (;;  +  3)...r 


■P 


After  this  problem  Pascal  adds. 

Hoc  problemate  tractatum  liiiuc  absolvere  constitiieram,  non  tamen 
omniiio  sine  molestia,  cum  niulta  alia  parata  liabeam  ;  sed  ubi  tanta 
ubertas,  vi  moderanda  eat  fames  :  his  ergo  pauca  hsec  subjiciam. 

Eruditissimus  ac  milii  charisimus,  D.D.  de  Ganieres,  circa  combina- 
tiones,  assiduo  ac  peiiitili  labore,  more  suo,  incumbens,  ac  indigens 
facili  constructione  ad  inveniendum  quoties  numerus  datus  in  alio  dato 
combinetur,  hanc  ipse  sibi  praxim  instituit. 

Pascal  then  gives  the  rule ;  it  amounts  to  this ;  the  num- 
ber of  combinations  of  r  things  taken  |)  at  a  time  is 

r  (>'-  1)...  {r-p+  1) 

■         {p        ■ 

This  is  the  form  with  which  we  are  now  most  familiar.  It 
may  be  immediately  shewn  to  agree  with  the  form  given  before 
by  Pascal,  by  cancelling  or  introducing  factors  into  both  numerator 
and  denominator.     Pascal  however  savs,  Excellentem  hanc  solu- 


.so  SniOOTEN. 

tionem  ipse  mihi  ostendit,  ac  etiam  demonstranJam  proposiiit,  ipsam 
ego  san^  miratus  sum,  sed  difficultate  territus  vix  opus  suscepi, 
et  ipsi  authori  relinquendum  existimavi;  attamen  trianguli  arith- 
metici  auxilio,  sic  proclivis  facta  est  via.  Pascal  then  establishes 
the  correctness  of  the  rule  by  the  aid  of  his  Arithmetical  Triangle; 
after  which  he  concludes  thus,  Hac  demonstratione  assecuta,  jam 
reliqua  quae  invitus  supprimebam  libenter  omitto,  adeo  dulce  est 
amicorum  memorari. 

42.  In  the  work  of  Schooten  to  which  w^e  have  already  re- 
ferred in  Art.  28  we  find  some  very  slight  remarks  on  combinations 
and  their  applications;  see  pages  873 — 403.  Schooten's  first  sec- 
tion is  entitled,  Ratio  inveniendi  electiones  omnes,  qu^  fieri  pos- 
sunt,  data  multitudine  rerum.  He  takes  four  letters  a,  h,  c,  d, 
and  arranges  them  thus, 

a. 

h.  ah. 

c.  ac.  he.  ahc. 

d.  ad.  hd.  abd.  cd.  acd.  bed.  abed. 

Thus  he  finds  that  15  elections  can  be  made  out  of  these  four 
letters.  So  he  adds,  Hinc  si  per  a  designatur  unum  malum,  jDer  b 
unum  pirum,  per  c  unum  prunum,  et  per  d  unum  cerasum,  et  ipsa 
alitor  atque  alitor,  ut  supra,  eligantur,  electio  eorum  fieri  poterit  15 
diversis  modis,  ut  sequitur 

Schooten  next  takes  five  letters ;  and  thus  he  infers  the  result 
which  we  should  now  express  by  saying  that,  if  there  are  n  letters 
the  whole  number  of  elections  is  2"—  1. 

Hence  if  a,  b,  c,  d  are  prime  factors  of  a  number,  and  all  dif- 
ferent, Schooten  infers  that  the  number  has  15  divisors  excludinsf 
unity  but  including  the  number  itself,  or  1 6  including  also  unity. 

Next  suppose  some  of  the  letters  are  repeated;  as  for  example 
suppose  we  have  a,  a,  b,  and  c ;  it  is  required  to  determine  how 
many  elections  can  be  made.    Schooten  arranges  the  letters  thus, 

a. 

a.  aa. 

h.  ah.  aab. 

c.  ac.  aac.  be.  ahc.  aabc. 
We  have  thus  2  +  3  +  6  elections. 


LEIBNITZ.  3 1 

Similarly  if  the  proposed  letters  are  a,  a,  a,  b,  h,  it  is  found 
that  11  elections  can  be  made. 

In  his  following  sections  Schooten  proceeds  to  apply  these 
results  to  questions  relating  to  the  number  of  divisors  in  a  number. 
Thus,  for  example,  supposing  a,  h,  c,  d,  to  be  different  prime 
factors,  numbers  of  the  following  forms  all  have  16  divisors, 
ahcd,  a^hc,  a^b^,  a^b,  a)^.  Hence  the  question  may  be  asked,  what  is 
the  least  number  which  has  10  divisors?  This  question  must 
be  answered  by  trial ;  we  must  take  the  smallest  prime  numbers 
2,  8,. . .  and  substitute  them  in  the  above  forms  and  pick  out  the  least 
number.  It  will  be  found  on  trial  that  the  least  number  is  2^.  3.  5, 
that  is  120.  Similarly,  suppose  we  require  the  least  number  which 
has  24  divisors.  The  suitable  forms  of  numbers  for  24  divisors 
are  ci^bcd,  a^¥c,  oJ'bc,  a^¥,  a'b'^,  o}^h  and  a^^.  It  will  be  found  on 
trial  that  the  least  number  is  2^  3^.  5,  that  is  360. 

Schooten  has  given  two  tables  connected  with  this  kind  of 
question.  (1)  A  table  of  the  algebraical  forms  of  numbers  which 
have  any  given  number  of  divisors  not  exceeding  a  hundred  ;  and 
in  this  table,  when  more  than  one  form  is  given  in  any  case,  the 
first  form  is  that  which  he  has  found  by  trial  will  give  the  least 
number  with  the  corresponding  number  of  divisors.  (2)  A  table 
of  the  least  numbers  which  have  any  assigned  number  of  divisors 
not  exceeding  a  hundred.  Schooten  devotes  ten  pages  to  a  list  of 
all  the  prime  numbers  under  10,000. 

43.  A  dissertation  was  pubHshed  by  Leibnitz  in  1666,  entitled 
Dissertatio  de  Arte  Combinatoma;  part  of  it  had  been  previously 
published  in  the  same  year  under  the  title  of  Disputatio  arith- 
metica  de  comjilexionihus.  The  dissertation  is  interesting  as  the 
earliest  work  of  Leibnitz  connected  with  mathematics ;  the  con- 
nexion however  is  very  slight.  The  dissertation  is  contained  in 
the  second  volume  of  the  edition  of  the  works  of  Leibnitz  by 
Dutens ;  and  in  the  first  volume  of  the  second  section  of  the 
mathematical  works  of  Leibnitz  edited  by  Gerhardt,  Halle,  1858. 
The  dissertation  is  also  included  in  the  collection  of  the  philoso- 
phical writings  of  Leibnitz  edited  by  Erdmann,  Berlin,  1840. 

44.  Leibnitz  constructs  a  table  at  the  beginning  of  his  dis- 


32  LEIBNITZ. 

sertation  similar  to  Pascal's  Arithmetical  Triangle,  and  applies  it 
to  find  the  number  of  the  combinations  of  an  assigned  set  of  things 
taken  two,  three,  four,... together.  In  the  latter  part  of  his  disser- 
tation Leibnitz  shews  how  to  obtain  the  number  of  permutations 
of  a  set  of  things  taken  all  together ;  and  he  forms  the  product  of 
the  first  24*  natural  numbers.  He  brings  forward  several  Latin 
lines,  including  that  which  we  have  already  quoted  in  Art.  39, 
and  notices  the  great  number  of  arrangements  which  can  be 
formed  of  them. 

The  greater  part  of  the  dissertation  however  is  of  such  a 
character  as  to  confirm  the  correctness  of  Erdmann's  judgment  in 
including  it  among  the  philosophical  works  of  Leibnitz.  Thus, 
for  example,  there  is  a  long  discussion  as  to  the  number  of  moods 
in  a  syllogism.  There  is  also  a  demonstration  of  the  existence  of 
the  Deity,  which  is  founded  on  three  definitions,  one  postulate, 
four  axioms,  and  one  result  of  observation,  namely,  aliquod  corpus 
movetur. 

4iD.     We  will  notice  some  points  of  interest  in  the  dissertation. 

(1)  Leibnitz  proposes  a  curious  mode  of  expression.  When 
a  set  of  things  is  to  be  taken  two  at  a  time  he  uses  the  S3rmbol 
com2natio  (combinatio)  ;  when  three  at  a  time  he  uses  conSnatio 
(conternatio) ;  when  four  at  a  time,  con4natio,  and  so  on. 

(2)  The  mathematical  treatment  of  the  subject  of  combina- 
tions is  far  inferior  to  that  given  by  Pascal ;  probably  Leibnitz 
had  not  seen  the  work  of  Pascal.  Leibnitz  seems  to  intimate 
that  his  predecessors  had  confined  themselves  to  the  combina- 
tions of  things  two  at  a  time,  and  that  he  had  himself  extended 
the  subject  so  far  as  to  shew  how  to  obtain  from  his  table  the 
combinations  of  things  taken  together  more  than  two  at  a  time  ; 
generaliorem  modum  nos  deteximus,  specialis  est  vidgatus.  He 
gives  the  rule  for  the  combination  of  things  two  at  a  time,  namely, 

that  which  we  now  express  by  the  formula         ^ — -^  ;  but  he  does 

not  give  the  similar  rule  for  combinations  three,  four,...  at  a  time, 
which  is  contained  in  Pascal's  work. 

(3)  After  giving  his  table,  which  is  analogous  to  the  Arith- 


LEIBNITZ.  S3 

metical  Triangle,  he  adds,  "Adjiciemus  hie  Theoremata  quorum 
TO  on  ex  ipsa  tabula  manifestum  est,  to  Slotl  ex  tabulae  funda- 
niento."  The  only  theorem  here  that  is  of  any  importance  is  that 
which  we  should  now  express  thus  :  if  n  be  prime  the  number  of 
combinations  of  n  things  taken  r  at  a  time  is  divisible  by  n. 

(4)  A  passage  in  which  Leibnitz  names  his  predecessors  may 
be  quoted.  After  saying  that  he  had  partly  furnished  the  matter 
himself  and  partly  obtained  it  from  others,  he  adds, 

Quis  ilia  primus  detexerit  ignoramus.  Scliwentenis  Belie.  1.  1,  Sect.  1, 
prop.  32,  apud  Hieronymum  Cardanum,  Johannem  Buteonem  et 
Nicolaum  Tartaleam,  extare  dicit.  In  Cardani  tameu  Practica  Arith- 
metica  quae  prodiit  Mediolani  anno  1539,  nihil  reperimus.  Inprimis 
dilucide,  quicquid  dudum  habetur,  proposuit  Christoph.  Clavius  in  Com. 
supra  Joh.  de  Sacro  Bosco  Spliaer.  edit.  Bomte  forma  4ta  anno  1785. 
p.  33.  seqq. 

With  respect  to  Schwenter  it  has  been  observ^ed, 

Schwenter  probably  alluded  to  Cardan  s  book,  "  De  Proportionibus," 
in  which  the  figurate  numbers  are  mentioned,  and  their  use  shown  in 
the  extraction  of  roots,  as  employed  by  Stifel,  a  German  algebraist, 
who  wrote  in  the  early  part  of  the  sixteenth  century.  Lubbock  and 
Drinkwater,  page  45. 

(5)  Leibnitz  uses  the  symbols  -1 =  in  their  present  sense  ; 

he  uses  -— ^  for  multiplication  and  --^  for  division.  He  uses  the 
word  productiun  in  the  sense  of  a  sum :  thus  he  calls  4  the  pro- 
ductum  of  3  +  1. 

46.  The  dissertation  shews  that  at  the  age  of  twenty  years 
the  distinguishing  characteristics  of  Leibnitz  were  strongly  de- 
veloped. The  extent  of  his  reading  is  indicated  by  the  numerous 
references  to  authors  on  various  subjects.  We  see  evidence  too 
that  he  had  already  indulged  in  those  dreams  of  impossible  achieve- 
ments in  which  his  vast  powers  were  uselessly  squandered.  He 
vainly  hoped  to  produce  substantial  realities  by  combining  the 
precarious  definitions  of  metaphysics  with  the  elementary  tniisms 
of  logic,  and  to  these  fruitless  attempts  he  gave  the  aspiring  titles 
of  universal  science,  general  science,  and  philosophical  calculus. 
See  Erdmann,  pages  82 — 91,  especially  page  84. 

3 


34  ^yALLIS. 

47.  A  discourse  of  coinhinations,  alternations,  and  aliquot 
parts  is  attached  to  the  English  edition  of  Wallis's  Algebra  pub- 
lished in  1685.  In  the  Latin  edition  of  the  Algebra,  published  in 
1693,  this  j^art  of  the  work  occupies  pages  485 — 529. 

In  referring  to  Wallis's  Algebra  we  shall  give  the  pages  of  the 
Latin  edition  ;  but  in  quoting  from  him  we  shall  adopt  his  own 
English  version.  The  English  version  was  reprinted  by  Maseres  in 
a  volume  of  reprints  which  was  published  at  London  in  1795  under 
the  title  of  The  Doctrine  of  Permutations  and  Gomhinations,  being 
an  essential  and  fundamental  part  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances. 

48.  "Wallis's  first  Chapter  is  Of  the  variety  of  Elections,  or 
Choise,  in  taking  or  leaving  One  or  more,  out  of  a  certain  Num- 
her  of  things  proposed.  He  draws  up  a  Table  which  agrees 
with  Pascal's  Arithmetical  Triangle,  and  shews  how  it  may  be 
used  in  finding  the  number  of  combinations  of  an  assigned  set 
of  things  taken  two,  three,  four,  five,...  at  a  time.  Wallis  does 
not  add  any  thing  to  what  Pascal  had  given,  to  whom  however 
he  does  not  refer ;  and  Wallis's  clumsy  parenthetical  style  con- 
trasts very  unfavourably  with  the  clear  bright  stream  of  thought 
and  language  which  flowed  from  the  genius  of  Pascal.  The 
chapter  closes  with  an  extract  from  the  Arithmetic  of  Buckley 
and  an  explanation  of  it ;  to  this  we  have  aU'eady  referred  in 
Art.  38. 

49.  Wallis's  second  Chapter  is  Of  Alternations,  or  the  different 
change  of  Order,  in  any  Number  of  things  ptroposed.  Here  he 
gives  some  examples  of  what  are  now  usually  called  permutations  ; 
thus  if  there  are  four  letters  a,  h,  c,  d,  the  number  of  permutations 
when  they  are  taken  all  together  is  4  x  3  x  2  x  1.  Wallis  accord- 
ingly exhibits  the  24  permutations  of  these  four  letters.  He  forms 
the  product  of  the  first  twenty-four  natural  numbers,  which  is  the 
number  of  the  permutations  of  twenty-four  things  taken  all  toge- 
ther. 

Wallis  exhibits  the  24  permutations  of  the  letters  in  the  word 
Roma  taken  all  together ;  and  then  he  subjoins,  *'  Of  which  (in 
Latin)  these  seven  are  only  useful;  Roma,  ramo,oram,mora,  maro, 
armo,  amor.  The  other  forms  are  useless ;  as  affording  no  (Latin) 
word  of  known  signification." 


WALLIS.  35 

Wallis  then  considers  the  case  in  which  there  is  some  repetition 
among  the  quantities  of  which  we  require  the  permutations.  He 
takes  the  letters  which  compose  the  word  Messes.  Here  if  there 
were  no  repetition  of  letters  the  number  of  permutations  of  the 
letters  taken  all  together  would^  be  1x2x3x4x5x0,  that  is 
720 ;  but  as  Wallis  explains,  owing  to  the  occurrence  of  the  letter 
e  twice,  and  of  the  letter  s  thrice,  the  number  720  must  be  divided 
by  2  X  2  X  3,  that  is  by  12.  Thus  the  number  of  permutations  is 
reduced  to  60.  Wallis  exhibits  these  permutations  and  then  sub- 
joins, "  Of  all  which  varieties,  there  is  none  beside  messes  itself, 
that  affords  an  useful  AnagTam."  The  chapter  closes  with  Wallis's 
attempt  at  determining  the  number  of  arrangements  of  the  verse 

Tot  tibi  sunt  dotes,  virgo,  quot  sidera  caelo. 

The  attempt  is  followed  by  these  w^ords,  "  I  will  not  be  posi- 
tive, that  there  may  not  be  some  other  Changes  :  (and  then,  those 
may  be  added  to  these :)  Or,  that  most  of  these  be  twice  repeated, 
(and  if  so,  those  are  to  be  abated  out  of  the  Number  :)  But  I  do 
not,  at  present,  discern  either  the  one  and  other." 

Wallis's  attempt  is  a  very  bad  specimen  of  analysis  ;  it  involves 
both  the  errors  he  himself  anticipates,  for  some  cases  are  omitted 
and  some  counted  more  than  once.  It  seems  strange  that  he 
should  have  failed  in  such  a  problem  considering  the  extraordinary 
powers  of  abstraction  and  memory  which  he  possessed ;  so  that 
as  he  states,  he  extracted  the  square  root  of  a  number  taken  at 
random  wdth  53  figures,  in  tenebris  decumbens,  sola  fretus 
memoria.     See  his  Algebra,  page  150. 

50.  Wallis's  third  Chapter  is  Of  the  Divisors  and  Aliquot 
paints,  of  a  Number  i^roposed.  This  Chapter  treats  of  the  resolu- 
tion of  a  number  into  its  prime  factors,  and  of  the  number  of 
divisors  Avhich  a  given  number  has,  and  of  the  least  numbers 
which  have  an  assigned  number  of  divisors. 

51.  Wallis's  fourth  Chapter  is  Monsieur  Fermafs Problems  con- 
cerning Divisors  and  Aliquot  Parts.  It  contains  solutions  of  two 
problems  which  Fermat  had  proposed  as  a  challenge  to  Wallis  and 
the  English  mathematicians.  The  problems  relate  to  what  is  now 
called  the  Theory  of  Numbers. 


o 

o- 


8G  PRESTET. 

52.  Thus  the  theory  of  combinations  is  not  applied  by  Wallis 
in  any  manner  that  materially  bears  upon  our  subject.  In  fact 
the  influence  of  Format  seems  to  have  been  more  powerful  than 
that  of  Pascal ;  and  the  Theory  of  Numbers  more  cultivated  than 
the  Theory  of  Probability. 

The  judgment  of  Montmort  seems  correct  that  nothing  of  any 
importance  in  the  Theory  of  Combinations  previous  to  his  own 
Avork  had  been  added  to  the  results  of  Pascal.  Montmort,  on  his 
page  XXXV,  names  as  writers  on  the  subject  Prestet,  Tacquet,  and 
Wallis.  I  have  not  seen  the  works  of  Prestet  and  Tacquet ; 
Gouraud  refers  to  Prestet's  Nouveaux  elements  de  mathematiqiies, 
2®  ed.,  in  the  following  terms,  Le  pere  Prestet,  enfin,  fort  habile 
geom^tre,  avait  explique  avec  infiniment  de  clart^,  en  1689,  les 
principaux  artifices  de  cet  art  ingenieux  de  composer  et  de  varier 
les  grandeurs.     Gouraud,  page  23. 


CHAPTER    V, 


MORTALITY  AND  LIFE  INSURANCE. 

53.  The  history  of  the  investigations  on  the  laws  of  mortality 
and  of  the  calculations  of  life  insurances  is  sufficiently  important 
and  extensive  to  demand  a  separate  work ;  these  subjects  were 
originally  connected  with  the  Theory  of  Probability  but  may  now 
be  considered  to  form  an  independent  kingdom  in  mathematical 
science :  we  shall  therefore  confine  ourselves  to  tracing  their 
origin. 

54.  According  to  Gouraud  the  use  of  tables  of  mortality  was 
not  quite  unknown  to  the  ancients:  after  speaking  of  such  a 
table  as  unkno'svn  until  the  time  of  John  de  Witt  he  subjoins 
in  a  note, 

Inconnue  du  moins  des  modernes.  Car  il  paraitrait  par  un  passage 
du  Digeste,  ad  legem  Falcidlam,  xxxv.  2,  68,  que  les  Romains  n'en 
ignoraieut  pas  absolument  I'usage.  Voyez  "k  ce  sujet  M.  Y.  Leclerc, 
Des  Journaux  chez  les  Romains,  p.  198,  et  une  curieuse  dissertation: 
De  prohabilitate  vitce  ejusqite  usu  forensi,  etc.,  d'un  certain  Schmelzer 
(Goettingue,  1787,  in-8).     Gouraud,  page  14. 

55.  The  first  name  which  is  usually  mentioned  in  connexion 
with  our  present  subject  is  that  of  John  Graunt :  I  borrow  a 
notice  of  him  from  Lubbock  and  Drinkwater,  page  4-i.  After 
referrino:  to  the  reoisters  of  the  annual  numbers  of  deaths  in 
London  which  began  to  be  kept  in  159:^,  and  which  with  some 


38  GRAUNT. 

intermissions  between  1d94<  and  1603  have  since  been  regularly 
continued,  they  proceed  thus. 

They  were  first  intended  to  make  known  the  progress  of  the  plague ; 
and  it  was  not  till  1662  that  Captain  Graunt,  a  most  acute  and  intel- 
ligent man,  conceived  the  idea  of  rendering  them  subservient  to  the 
ulterior  objects  of  determining  the  population  and  growth  of  the  me- 
tropolis ;  as  before  his  time,  to  use  his  own  words,  "  most  of  them  who 
constantly  took  in  the  weekly  bills  of  mortality,  made  little  or  no  use 
of  them  than  so  as  they  might  take  the  same  as  a  text  to  talk  upon  in 
the  next  company;  and  withal,  in  the  plague  time,  how  the  sickness 
increased  or  decreased,  that  so  the  rich  might  guess  of  the  necessity  of 
their  removal,  and  tradesmen  might  conjecture  what  doings  they  were 
like  to  have  in  their  respective  dealings."  Graunt  was  careful  to  pub- 
lish with  his  deductions  the  actual  returns  from  which  they  were 
obtained,  comparing  himself,  when  so  doing,  to  "a  silly  schoolboy, 
coming  to  say  his  lesson  to  the  world  (that  peevish  and  tetchie  master,) 
who  brings  a  bundle  of  rods,  wherewith  to  be  whipped  for  every  mistake 
he  has  committed."  Many  subsequent  writers  have  betrayed  more  fear 
of  the  punishment  they  might  be  liable  to  on  making  similar  disclosures, 
and  have  kept  entirely  out  of  sight  the  sources  of  their  conclusions. 
The  immunity  they  have  thus  purchased  from  contradiction  could  not 
be  obtained  but  at  the  expense  of  confidence  in  their  results. 

These  researches  procured  for  Graunt  the  honour  of  being  chosen  a 
fellow  of  the  Koyal  Society,  . . . 

Gouraud  says  in  a  note  on  his  page  16, 

...John  Graunt,  homme  sans  geometric,  mais  qui  ne  manquait  ni 
de  sagacite  ni  de  bon  sens,  avait,  dans  une  sorte  de  traite  d'Arithme- 
tique  politique  intitule:  Natural  and  'political  observations .. .made  itpon 
the  hills  of  mortality^  etc.,  rassemble  ces  difierentes  listes,  et  donne  meme 
i^ihid.  chap,  xi.)  un  calcul,  a  la  verite  fort  grossier,  mais  du  moins  fort 
original,  de  la  mortalite  probable  \  chaque  age  d'un  certain  nombre 
d'individus  supposes  n6s  viables  tons  au  meme  instant. 

See  also  the  AtJienceum  for  October  31st,  1863,  page  537. 

56.     The  names  of  two  Dutchmen  next  present  themselves, 

Van  Hudden  and  John  de  Witt.    Montucla  says,  page  407, 

Le  probleme  des  rentes  viageres  fut  traite  par  Van  Hudden,  qui 
quoique  geometre,  ne  laissa  pas  que  d'etre  bourguemestre  d' Amsterdam, 


JOHN   DE   WITT.  30 

et  par  le  c61ebre  pensionnaire  d'Hollande,  Jean  de  Witfc,  iin  dea  pre^ 
miers  promoteurs  de  la  geometrie  de  Descartes.  Jlgnore  le  titre  de 
I'ecrit  de  Hudden,  mais  celui  de  Jean  de  Witt  etoit  intitule :  De  vardye 
van  de  lif-renten  na  j^^oportie  van  de  los-renten,  ou  la  Valeur  des  rentes 
viageres  en  raison  des  ventes  lihres  ou  remboursahles  (La  Haye,  1C71). 
lis  etoient  I'un  et  I'autre  plus  a  portee  que  personne  d'en  sentir  I'impor- 
tance  et  de  se  procurer  les  depouillemens  necessaires  de  registres  de  inor- 
talitc;  aussi  Leibnitz,  passant  en  Hollande  quelques  annees  apres,  fit 
tout  son  possible  pour  se  procurer  I'ecrit  de  Jean  de  Witt,  mais  il  ne 
pent  y  parvenir;  il  n'etoit  cependant  pas  absolument  perdu,  car  M.  Ni- 
colas Struyck  {Inleiding  tot  het  algemeine  geography,  &c.  Amst.  1740, 
in  4o.  p.  345)  nous  apprend  qu'il  en  a  eu  un  exemj)laire  entre  les  mains; 
il  nous  en  donne  un  precis,  par  lequel  on  voit  combien  Jean  de  Witt 
raisonnoit  juste  sur  cette  matiere. 

Le  chevalier  Petty,  Anglois,  qui  s'occupa  beaucoup  de  calculs  poli- 
tiques,  entrevit  le  probleme,  mais  il  n'etoit  pas  assez  geometre  pour  le 
traiter  fructueusement,  en  sorte  que,  jusqu'a  Halley,  I'Angleterre  et  la 
France  qui  emprunterent  tant  et  ont  tant  empruntc  de2:)uis,  le  firent 
comme  des  aveugles  ou  comme  de  jeunes  debauclics. 

57.  Witli  respect  to  Sir  William  Petty,  to  whom  Montucla 
refers,  we  may  remark  that  his  writings  do  not  seem  to  Iiave  been 
very  important  in  connexion  with  our  present  subject.  Some 
account  of  them  is  given  in  the  article  A  rithmetique  Politique  of 
the  original  French  Encyclopedie ;  the  article  is  reproduced  in 
the  Encyclopedie  Methodique.  Gouraud  speaks  of  Petty  thus  in  a 
note  on  his  page  1 6, 

Apres  Graunt,  le  chevalier  W.  Petty,  dans  differents  essais  d'eco- 
nomie  politique,  oi\  il  y  avait,  il  est  vrai,  plus  d 'imagination  que  de 
jugement,  s'etait,  de  1682  a  1687,  occupe  de  semblables  recherclies. 

58.  W^ith  respect  to  Van  Hudden  to  whom  Montucla  also 
refers  we  can  only  add  that  his  name  is  mentioned  with  appro- 
bation by  Leibnitz,  in  conjunction  with  that  of  John  de  Witt, 
for  his  researches  on  annuities.  See  Leihnitii  Opera  Omnia,  ed. 
Dutens,  Vol.  II.  part  1,  page  93  ;  Vol.  Yl.  part  1,  page  217. 

69.  With  respect  to  the  work  of  John  de  Witt  we  have 
some  notices  in  the  correspondence  between  Leibnitz  and  James 
Bernoulli;  but  these  notices  do  not  literallv  confirm  Montucla's 


40  JOHN   DE  WITT. 

statement  respecting  Leibnitz :  see  Leihnizens  Matliematische 
Schriften  herausgegehen  von  C.  I.  Gerhardt,  Erste  Abtheilung. 
Band  ill.  Halle  1855.     James  Bernoulli  says,  page  78, 

Nuper  in  Menstruis  Excerptis  Hanoverae  imjoressis  citatum,  inveni 
Tractatum  quendam  mihi  ignotum  Pensionarii  de  Wit  von  Subtiler 
Ausreclinung  des  valoris  der  Leib-Renten.  Fortasse  is  quaedam  hue 
facientia  liabet;  quod  si  sit,  copiam  ejus  mihi  alieunde  fieri  percuperem. 

In  liis  reply  Leibnitz  says,  page  84, 

Pensionarii  de  Wit  libellus  exiguus  est,  ubi  aestimatione  ilia  nota 
utitur  a  possibilitate  casuum  aequalium  aequali  et  liinc  ostendit  re- 
ditus  ad  vitam  sufiicientes  pro  sorte  a  Batavis  solvi.  Ideo  Belgice 
scripserat,  ut  aequitas  in  vulgus  apjDareret. 

In  his  next  letter,  page  89,  James  Bernoulli  says  that  De 
Witt's  book  will  be  useful  to  him;  and  as  he  had  in  vain  tried 
to  obtain  it  from  Amsterdam  he  asks  for  the  loan  of  the  copy 
which  Leibnitz  possessed.     Leibnitz  replies,  page  93, 

Pensionarii  Wittii  dissertatio,  vel  potius  Scheda  impressa  de  re- 
ditibus  ad  vitam,  sane  brevis,  extat  quidem  inter  chartas  meas,  sed  cum 
ad  Te  mittere  vellem,  reperire  nondum  potui.  Dabo  tamen  operam  ut 
nanciscare,  ubi  primum  domi  eruere  licebit  alicubi  latitantem. 

James  Bernoulli  again  asked  for  the  book,  page  95.  Leibnitz 
replies,  page  99, 

Pensionarii  Wittii  scriptum  nondum  satis  quaerere  licuit  inter  char- 
tas; non  dubito  tamen,  quin  sim  tandem  reperturus,  ubi  vacaverit. 
Sed  vix  aliquid  in  eo  novum  Tibi  occurret,  cum  fundamentis  iisdem 
ubique  insistat,  quibus  cum  alii  viri  docti  jam  erant  usi,  tum  Paschalius 
in  Triangulo  Aritlimetico,  et  Hugenius  in  diss,  de  Alea,  nempe  ut 
medium  Arithmeticum  inter  aeque  incerta  sumatur;  quo  fundamento 
etiam  rustic!  utuntur,  cum  praediorum  pretia  aestimant,  et  rerum  fis- 
calium  curatores,  cum  reditus  praefecturarum  Principis  medios  consti- 
tuunt,   quando  se  offert  conductor. 

In  the  last  of  his  letters  to  James  Bernoulli  which  is  given,  Leib- 
nitz implies  that  he  has  not  yet  found  the  book  ;  see  page  103. 

We  find  from  pages  767,  769  of  the  volume  that  Leibnitz 
attempted  to  procure  a  copy  of  De  Witt's  dissertation  by  the  aid 
of  John  Bernoulli,  but  without  success. 

These  letters  were  written  in  the  years  1703,  1704,  1705. 


HALLEY.  41 

60.  The  political  fame  of  John  de  Witt  has  overpowered 
that  which  he  might  have  gained  from  science,  and  thus  his  mathe- 
matical attainments  are  rarely  noticed.  We  may  therefore  add 
that  he  is  said  to  have  published  a  work  entitled  Elementa  linea- 
rum  curvarum,  Leyden  1650,  which  is  commended  by  Condorcet ; 
see  Condorcet's  Essai...d'Analyse...  i>age  CLXXXiv. 

CI.  We  have  now  to  notice  a  memoir  by  Halley,  entitled  An 
estimate  of  the  Degrees  of  the  Mortality  of  Mankind,  dravm  from 
carious  Tables  of  the  Births  and  Funerals  at  the  City  of  Breslaiv; 
with  an  Attempt  to  ascertain  the  Price  of  Annuities  upon  Lives. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  Vol.  xvil.  of  the  Philosophical 
Transactions,  1693  ;  it  occupies  pages  596 — 610. 

This  memoir  is  justly  celebrated  as  having  laid  the  foundations 
of  a  correct  theory  of  the  value  of  life  annuities. 

62.  Halley  refers  to  the  bills  of  mortality  which  had  been 
published  for  London  and  Dublin ;  but  these  bills  were  not  suit- 
able for  drawing  accurate  deductions. 

First,  In  that  the  Number  of  the  People  was  wanting.  Secondly, 
That  the  Ages  of  the  People  d}dng  was  not  to  be  had.  And  Lastly, 
That  both  London  and  Dublin  by  reason  of  the  great  and  casual 
Accession  of  Strangers  who  die  therein,  (as  appeared  in  both,  by  the 
great  Excess  of  the  Funerals  above  the  Births)  rendered  them  incapable 
of  being  Standards  for  this  purpose;  which  requires,  if  it  were  possible, 
that  the  People  we  treat  of  should  not  at  all  be  changed,  but  die  where 
they  were  born,  without  any  Adventitious  Increase  from  Abroad,  or 
Decay  by  Migration  elsewhere. 

63.  Halley  then  intimates  that  he  had  found  satisfactory  data 
in  the  Bills  of  Mortality  for  the  city  of  Breslau  for  the  years 
1687,  88,  89,  90,  91 ;  which  *'had  then  been  recently  communi- 
cated by  Neumann  (probably  at  Halley's  request)  through  Justell, 
to  the  Royal  Society,  in  whose  archives  it  is  supposed  that  copies 
of  the  original  registers  are  still  preserved."  Lubbock  and  Drink- 
luater,  page  45. 

64.  The  Breslau  registers  do  not  appear  to  have  been  pub- 
lished themselves,  and  Halley  gives  only  a  very  brief  introduction 


42  HALLEY. 

to  the  table  which  he  deduced  from  them.     Halley's  table  is  in  the 
following  form: 


1 

2 
3 
4 


1000 
855 

798 
760 


The  left-hand  number  indicates  ages  and  the  right-hand  num- 
ber the  corresponding  number  of  persons  alive.  We  do  not  feel 
confident  of  the  meaning  of  the  table.  Montucla,  page  408,  under- 
stood that  out  of  1000  persons  born,  855  attain  to  the  age  of  one 
year,  then  798  out  of  these  attain  to  the  age  of  two  years,  and 
so  on. 

Daniel  Bernoulli  understood  that  the  number  of  infants  born 
is  not  named,  but  that  1000  are  supposed  to  reach  one  year,  then 
855  out  of  these  reach  two  years,  and  so  on.  Hist  de  VAcad. ... 
Paris,  1760. 

^D.  Halley  proceeds  to  shew  the  use  of  his  table  in  the  calcu- 
lation of  annuities.  To  find  the  value  of  an  annuity  on  the  life  of 
a  given  person  we  must  take  from  the  table  the  chance  that  he 
will  be  alive  after  the  lapse  of  n  years,  and  multiply  this  chance 
by  the  present  value  of  the  annual  payment  due  at  the  end  of 
n  years  ;  we  must  then  sum  the  results  thus  obtained  for  all  values 
of  n  from  1  to  the  extreme  possible  age  for  the  life  of  the  given 
person.  Halley  says  that  "  This  will  without  doubt  appear  to 
be  a  most  laborious  Calculation."  He  gives  a  table  of  the  value 
of  an  annuity  for  every  fifth  year  of  age  up  to  the  seventieth. 

^Q.  He  considers  also  the  case  of  annuities  on  joint  lives,  or 
on  one  of  two  or  more  lives.  Suppose  that  we  have  two  persons, 
an  elder  and  a  younger,  and  we  wish  to  know  the  probability 
of  one  or  both  being  alive  at  the  end  of  a  given  number  of  years. 
Let  N  be  the  number  in  the  table  opposite  to  the  present  age  of 
the  younger  person,  and  R  the  number  opposite  to  that  age  in- 
creased by  the  given  number  of  years  ;  and  let  N=R-\-  Y,  so  that 
Y  represents  the  number  who  have  died  out  of  N  in  the  given 
number  of  years.  Let  n,  r,  y  denote  similar  quantities  for  the 
elder  age.     Then  the  chance  that  both  will  be  dead  at  the  end 


HALLEY 


43 


of  the  given  number  of  years  is  —■ ;  the  chance  that  the  younger 

Till 

will  be  alive  and  the  elder  dead  is  -r^  ;  and  so  on. 

Halley  gives  according  to  the  fashion  of  the  time  a  geometri- 
cal illustration. 


D 
1 


B 


E  _C 


G 


H 


Let  AB  or  CD  represent  N,  and  DE  or  BH  represent  R, 
so  that  EC  or  HA  represents  F.  Similarly  AC,  AF,  CF  may 
represent  n,  r,  y.  Then  of  course  the  rectangle  ECFG  represents 
Ty,  and  so  on. 

In  like  manner,  Halley  first  gives  the  proposition  relating  to 
three  lives  in  an  algebraical  form,  and  then  a  geometrical  illus- 
tration by  means  of  a  parallelepiped.  We  find  it  difficult  in 
the  present  day  to  understand  how  such  simple  algebraical  pro- 
positions could  be  rendered  more  intelligible  by  the  aid  of  areas 
and  solids. 

67.  On  pages  654^ — 6oQ  of  the  same  volume  of  the  Pliiloso- 
pMcal  Transactions  we  have  Some  further  Considerations  on  the 
Breslaiu  Bills  of  Mortality.     By  the  same  Hand,  d'C. 

68.  De  Moivre  refers  to  Halley's  memoir,  and  republishes 
the  table;  see  Be  Moivre's  Doctrine  of  Chances,  pages  261,  ^^o. 


CHAPTER    VI. 

MISCELLANEOUS  INVESTIGATIONS 
Between  the  yeaes  1670  and  1700. 

69.  The  present  chapter  will  contain  notices  of  various  con- 
tributions to  our  subject,  which  were  made  between  the  publi- 
cation of  the  treatise  by  Huygens  and  of  the  more  elaborate 
works  by  James  Bernoulli,  Montmort,  and  De  Moivre. 

70.  A  Jesuit  named  John  Caramuel  published  in  1670,  under 
the  title  of  Mathesis  Bicej^s,  two  folio  volumes  of  a  course  of 
Mathematics  ;  it  appears  from  the  list  of  the  author's  works  at  the 
beginning  of  the  first  volume  that  the  entire  course  was  to  have 
comprised  four  volumes. 

There  is  a  section  called  Gomhinatoria  which  occupies  pages 
921 — 1036,  and  part  of  this  is  devoted  to  our  subject. 

Caramuel  gives  first  an  account  of  combinations  in  the  modern 
sense  of  the  word;  there  is  nothing  requiring  special  attention 
here  :  the  work  contains  the  ordinary  results,  not  proved  by  general 
symbols  but  exhibited  by  means  of  examples.  Caramuel  refers 
often  to  Clavius  and  Izquierdus  as  his  guides. 

After  this  account  of  combinations  in  the  modern  sense  Cara- 
muel proceeds  to  explain  the  Ars  Lidliana,  that  is  the  method  of 
affording  assistance  in  reasoning,  or  rather  in  disputation,  proposed 
by  Raymond  Lully. 

71.  Afterwards  we  have  a  treatise  on  chances  under  the  title 
of  Kyheia,  quce  Combinatorioe  genus  est,  de  Alea,  et  Ludis  FortuncB 


CARAMUEL.  45 

serio  disputans.  This  treatise  includes  a  reprint  of  tlie  treatise  of 
Huygens,  which  however  is  attributed  to  another  person.  Cara- 
muel  says,  page  984, 

Dum  hoc  Syntagma  Perilhistri  Domino  N.  Viro  eruditissimo  com- 
municarem,  ostendit  etiam  mihi  ingeniosam  quamdam  de  eodem  argu- 
ment© Diatribam,  quam  ^  Christiano  Severino  Longomontano  fuisse 
scriptam  putabat,  et,  quia  est  curiosa,  et  brevis,  debuit  huic  Qusestioni 
subjungi... 

In  the  table  of  contents  to  his  work,  page  xxviii,  Caramuel 
speaks  of  the  tract  of  Huygens  as 

Diatribe  ingeniose  a  Longomontano,  ut  putatur,  de  hoc  eodem  argu- 
mento  scripta :  nescio  an  evulgata. 

Longomontanus  was  a  Danish  astronomer  who  lived  from  15G2 
to  1647. 

72.  Nicolas  Bernoulli  speaks  very  severely  of  Caramuel.  He 
says  XJn  Jesuite  nomme  Caramuel,  que  j'ai  citd  dans  ma  These... 
mais  comme  tout  ce  qu'il  donne  n'est  qu'un  amas  de  paralogismes, 
je  ne  le  compte  pour  rien.     Montmort,  p.  387. 

By  his  T}ie$e  Nicolas  Bernoulli  probably  means  his  Specimina 
Artis  conjectandi...,  which  will  be  noticed  in  a  subsequent  Chapter, 
but  Caramuel's  name  is  not  mentioned  in  that  essay  as  reprinted 
in  the  A  da  Erud. . . .  Suppl. 

John  Bernoulli  in  a  letter  to  Leibnitz  speaks  more  favourably 
of  Caramuel ;  see  page  715  of  the  volume  cited  in  Art.  59. 

73.  Nicolas  Bernoulli  has  exaggerated  the  Jesuit's  blunders. 
Caramuel  touches  on  the  following  points,  and  correctly :  the 
chances  of  the  throws  with  two  dice ;  simple  cases  of  the  Problem 
of  Points  for  two  players ;  the  chance  of  throwing  an  ace  once  at 
least  in  two  throws,  or  in  three  throws  ;  the  game  of  Passe-dix. 

He  goes  Avrong  in  trying  the  Problem  of  Points  for  three 
players,  which  he  does  for  two  simple  cases ;  and  also  in  two  other 
problems,  one  of  which  is  the  fourteenth  of  Huygens's  treatise,  and 
the  otlier  is  of  exactly  the  same  kind. 

Caramuel's  method  with  the  fourteenth  problem  of  Huygens's 
treatise  is  as  follows.    Suppose  the  stake  to  be  36  ;  then  A's  chance 


46  SAUVEUR. 

5  5 

at  his  first  throw  is  ^ ,  and  ^  x  86  =  5 ;  thus  taking  5  from  86  we 

may  consider  81  as  left  for  B.    Now  B's  chance  of  success  in  a  single 

throw  is  ^  ;  thus  —  x  81,  that  is  5  J,  may  be  considered  the  value 
oO  oO 

of  his  first  throw. 

Thus  Caramuel  assigns  5  to  J.  and  5  J  to  B,  as  the  value  of 

their  first  throws  respectively ;  then  the  remaining  25f  he  proposes 

to  divide  equally  between  A  and  B.     This  is  wrong :  he  ought  to 

have  continued  his  process,  and  have  assigned  to  A  for  his  second 

5  6 

throw  ^  of  the  25f ,  and  then  to  B  for  his  second  throw  -^  of  the 

remainder ;  and  so  on.  Thus  he  Avould  have  had  for  the  shares  of 
each  player  an  infinite  geometrical  progression,  and  the  result 
would  have  been  correct. 

It  is  strange  that  Caramuel  went  wrong  when  he  had  the 
treatise  of  Huygens  to  guide  him ;  it  seems  clear  that  he  followed 
this  oruidance  in  the  discussion  of  the  Problem  of  Points  for  Uvo 
players,  and  then  deserted  it. 

74.  In  the  Journal  des  Scavans  for  Feb.  1679,  Sauveur  gave 
some  formulae  without  demonstration  relating  to  the  advantage  of 
the  Banker  at  the  game  of  Bassette.  Demonstrations  of  the  for- 
mulae will  be  found  in  the  Ars  Conjectandi  of  James  Bernoulli, 
pages  191 — 199.  I  have  examined  Sauveur's  formulae  as  given 
in  the  Amsterdam  edition  of  the  Journal.  There  are  six  series 
of  formulae  ;  in  the  first  five,  which  alone  involve  any  difficulty, 
Sauveur  and  Bernoulli  agree :  the  last  series  is  obtained  by  simply 
subtracting  the  second  from  the  fifth,  and  in  this  case  by  mistake 
or  misprint  Sauveur  is  wrong.  Bernoulli  seems  to  exaggerate  the 
discrepancy  when  he  says,  Qu5d  si  quis  D.ni  Salvatoris  Tabellas 
cum  hisce  nostris  contulerit,  deprehendet  illas  in  quibusdam  locis, 
praesertim  ultimis,  nonnihil  emendationis  indigere.  Montucla, 
page  390,  and  Gouraud,  page  17,  seem  also  to  think  Sauveur  more 
inaccurate  than  he  really  is. 

An  eloge  of  Sauveur  by  Fontenelle  is  given  in  the  volume 
for  1716  of  the  Hist,  de  F Acad.... Paris.  Fontenelle  says  that 
Bassette  was  more  beneficial  to  Sauveur  than  to  most  of  those  who 


LEIBXITZ.  47 

played  at  it  with  so  much  fury ;  it  was  at  the  request  of  the  Marquis 
of  Dangeau  that  Sauveur  undertook  the  investigation  of  the 
chances  of  the  game.  Sauveur  was  in  consequence  introduced  at 
court,  and  had  the  honour  of  explaining  his  calculations  to  the 
King  and  Queen.     See  also  Montmor^t,  page  xxxix. 

75.  James  Bernoulli  proposed  for  solution  two  problems  in 
chances  in  the  Journal  des  Sgavans  for  1685.  They  are  as 
follows : 

1.  A  and  B  play  with  a  die,  on  condition  that  he  who  first 
throws  an  ace  wins.  First  A  throws  once,  then  B  throws  once, 
then  A  throws  twice,  then  B  throws  twice,  then  A  throws  three 
times,  then  B  throws  three  times,  and  so  on  until  ace  is  thrown. 

2.  Or  first  A  throws  once,  then  B  twice,  then  A  three  times, 
then  B  four  times,  and  so  on. 

The  problems  remained  unsolved  until  James  Bernoulli  himself 
gave  the  results  in  the  Acta  Eruditorum  for  1690.  Afterwards  in 
the  same  volume  Leibnitz  gave  the  rcsidts.  The  chances  involve 
infinite  series  which  are  not  summed. 

James  Bernoulli's  solutions  are  reprinted  in  the  collected 
edition  of  his  works,  Geneva,  17^4  ;  see  pages  207  and  430.  The 
problems  are  also  solved  in  the  Ars  Conjectandi,  pages  52 — oG. 

76.  Leibnitz  took  great  interest  in  the  Theory  of  Probability 
and  shewed  that  he  was  fully  alive  to  its  importance,  although  he 
cannot  be  said  himself  to  have  contributed  to  its  advance.  There 
was  one  subject  which  especially  attracted  his  attention,  namely 
that  of  games  of  all  kinds ;  he  himself  here  found  an  exercise  for 
his  inventive  powers.  He  believed  that  men  had  noAvhere  shewn 
more  ingenuity  than  in  their  amusements,  and  that  even  those  of 
children  might  usefully  engage  the  attention  of  the  greatest  mathe- 
maticians. He  wished  to  have  a  systematic  treatise  on  games, 
comprising  first  those  which  depended  on  numbers  alone,  secondly 
those  which  depended  on  position,  like  chess,  and  lastly  those 
which  depended  on  motion,  like  billiards.  This  he  considered 
would  be  useful  in  bringing  to  perfection  the  art  of  invention,  or 


48  ARBUTHXOT. 

as  he  expresses  it  in  another  place,  in  bringing  to  perfection  the 
art  of  arts,  which  is  the  art  of  thinking. 

See  Leihnitii  Opera  Omnia,  ed.  Dutens,  Vol.  v.  pages  17,  22,  28, 
29,  203,  206.    Vol.  Vi.  part  1,  271,  304.    Erdmann,  page  175. 

See  also  Opera  Omnia,  ed.  Dutens,  Vol.  vi.  part  1,  page  36, 
for  the  design  which  Leibnitz  entertained  of  writing  a  work  on 
estimating  the  probability  of  conclusions  obtained  by  arguments. 

77.  Leibnitz  however  furnishes  an  example  of  the  liability  to 
error  which  seems  peculiarly  characteristic  of  our  subject.  He 
says.  Opera  Omnia,  ed.  Dutens,  Vol.  vi.  part  1,  page  217, 

...par  exemple,  avec  deux  des,  il  est  aussi  faisable  de  jetter  douze 
points,  que  d'en  jetter  onze ;  car  Tun  et  I'autre  no  se  peut  faire  que 
d'une  seule  manierej  mais  il  est  trois  fois  plus  faisable  d'en  jetter 
sept;  car  cela  se  peut  faire  en  jettant  six  et  un,  cinq  et  deux,  quatre 
et  trois;  et  une  combinaison  ici  est  aussi  faisable  que  I'autre. 

It  is  true  that  eleven  can  only  be  made  up  of  six  and  five  ;  but 
the  six  may  be  on  either  of  the  dice  and  the  five  on  the  other,  so 
that  the  chance  of  throwing  eleven  with  two  dice  is  twice  as  great 
as  the  chance  of  throwing  twelve :  and  similarly  the  chance  of 
throwing  seven  is  six  times  as  great  as  the  chance  of  throwing 
twelve. 

78.  A  work  entitled  Of  the  Laws  of  Chance  is  said  by  Montu- 
cla  to  have  appeared  at  London  in  1692;  he  adds  mais  n'ayant 
jamais  rencontr^  ce  livre,  je  ne  puis  en  dire  davantage.  Je  le 
soupconne  n^anmoins  de  Benjamin  Motte,  depuis  secretaire  de 
la  society  royale.     Montucla,  page   391. 

Lubbock  and  Drink  water  say  respecting  it,  page  43, 
This  essay,  which  was  edited,  and  is  generally  supposed  to  have 
been  written  by  Motte,  the  secretary  of  the  Koyal  Society,  contains 
a  translation  of  Huyghens's  treatise,  and  an  ajDplication  of  his  princi- 
ples to  the  determination  of  the  advantage  of  the  banker  at  pharaon, 
hazard,  and  other  games,  and  to  some   questions  relating  to  lotteries. 

A  similar  statement  is  made  by  Galloway  in  his  Treatise  on 
Prohahility,  page  5. 

79.  It  does  not  appear  however  that  there  was  any  fellow 
of  the  Royal  Society  named  Motte;  for  the  name  does  not  occur 


ARBUTHNOT.  49 

in  the   list   of  fellows  given  in  Thomson's  History  of  the  Royal 
Society. 

I  have  no  doubt  that  the  work  is  due  to  Arbuthnot.  For 
there  is  an  English  translation  of  Huygens's  treatise  by  W. 
Browne,  published  in  1714  ;  in  his  Advertisement  to  the  Reader 
Browne  says,  speaking  of  Huygens's  treatise, 

Besides  the  Latin  Editions  it  has  pass'd  thro',  the  learned  Dr 
Arbuthnott  publish'd  an  English  one,  together  with  an  Application 
of  the  General  Doctrine  to  some  pai-ticular  Games  then  most  in  use; 
which  is  so  intirely  dispers'd  Abroad,  that  an  Account  of  it  is  all  we 
can  now  meet  with. 

This  seems  to  imply  that  there  had  been  no  other  transla- 
tion except  Arbuthnot's;  and  the  words  ''an  Application  of  the 
General  Doctrine  to  some  particular  Games  then  most  in  use" 
agree  very  well  with  some  which  occur  in  the  work  itself:  ''It 
is  easy  to  apply  this  method  to  the  Games  that  are  in  use  amongst 
us."     See  page  28  of  the  fourth  edition. 

Watt's  Bihliotheca  Britannica,  under  the  head  Arbuthnot,  places 
the  work  with  the  date  1G92. 

80.  I  have  seen  only  one  copy  of  this  book,  which  was  lent 
to  me  by  Professor  De  Morgan.     The  title  page  is  as  follows: 

Of  the  laws  of  chance,  or,  a  method  of  calculation  of  the  hazards 
of  game,  plainly  demonstrated,  and  applied  to  games  at  present  most 
in  use;  which  may  be  easily  extended  to  the  most  intricate  cases  of 
chance  imaginable.  The  fourth  edition,  ro^is'd  by  John  Ham.  By 
whom  is  added,  a  demonstration  of  the  gain  of  the  banker  in  any 
circumstance  of  the  game  call'd  Pharaon;  and  how  to  determine  the 
odds  at  the  Ace  of  Hearts  or  Fair  Chance;  with  the  arithmetical 
solution  of  some  questions  relating  to  lotteries;  and  a  few  remarks 
upon  Hazard  and  Backgammon.  London.  Printed  for  B.  Motte  and 
C.  Bathurst,  at  the  Middle-Temple  Gate  in  Fleet-street,  jt.dcc.xxxviii. 

81.  I  proceed  to  describe  the  work  as  it  appears  in  the 
fourth  edition. 

The  book  is  of  small  octavo  size;  it  may  be  said  to  consist  of 
two  parts.  The  first  part  extends  to  page  49 ;  it  contains  a  trans- 
lation of  Huygens's  treatise  with  some  additional  matter.  Page  50 
is  blank  ;  page  51  is  in  fact  a  title  page   containing  a  reprint 

4. 


50  ARBUTHNOT. 

of  part  of  the  title  we  have  already  given,  namely  from   "a  de- 
monstration" down  to  "Backgammon." 

The  words  which  have  been  quoted  from  Lubbock  and  Drink- 
water  in  Art.  78,  seem  not  to  distinguish  between  these  two 
parts.  There  is  nothing  about  the  "  advantage  of  the  banker 
at  Pharaon"  in  the  first  part;  and  the  investigations  which  are 
given  in  the  second  part  could  not,  I  believe,  have  appeared  so 
early  as  1692:  they  seem  evidently  taken  from  De  Moivre.  De 
Moivre  says  in  the  second  paragraph  of  his  preface, 

I  had  not  at  that  time  read  anything  concerning  this  Subject,  hut 
Mr.  Huygens's  Book,  de  Eatiociniis  in  Ludo  Alese,  and  a  little  Eng- 
lish Piece  (which  was  properly  a  Translation  of  it)  done  by  a  very  in- 
genious Gentleman,  who,  tho'  capable  of  carrying  the  matter  a  great 
deal  farther,  was  contented  to  follow  his  Original;  adding  only  to  it 
the  computation  of  the  Advantage  of  the  Setter  in  the  Play  called 
Hazard,  and  some  few  things  more. 

82.  The  work  is  preceded  by  a  Preface  written  with  vigour 
but  not  free  from  coarseness.  We  will  give  some  extracts,  which 
show  that  the  writer  was  sound  in  his  views  and  sagacious  in 
his  expectations. 

It  is  thought  as  necessary  to  write  a  Preface  before  a  Book,  as 
it  is  judg'd  civil,  when  you  invite  a  Friend  to  Dinner  to  proffer  him 
a  Glass  of  Hock  beforehand  for  a  Whet:  And  this  being  maim'd 
enough  for  want  of  a  Dedication,  I  am  resolv'd  it  shall  not  want  an' 
Epistle  to  the  Beader  too.  I  shall  not  take  upon  me  to  determine, 
whether  it  is  lawful  to  play  at  Dice  or  not,  leaving  that  to  be  disputed 
betwixt  the  Fanatick  Parsons  and  the  Sharpers ;  I  am  sure  it  is  lawful 
to  deal  with  Dice  as  with  other  Epidemic   Distempers; 

A  great  part  of  this  Discourse  is  a  Translation  from  Mons.  Huy- 
gens's Treatise,  De  ratiociniis  in  ludo  Alese;  one,  who  in  his  Improve- 
ments of  Philosophy,  has  but  one  Superior,  and  I  think  few  or  no 
equals.  The  whole  I  undertook  for  my  own  Divertisement,  next  to 
the  Satisfaction  of  some  Friends,  who  would  now  and  then  be  wran- 
gling about  the  Proportions  of  Hazards  in  some  Cases  that  are  here 
decided.  All  it  requir'd  was  a  few  spare  Hours,  and  but  little  Work 
for  the  Brain;  my  Design  in  publishing  it,  was  to  make  it  of  more 
general  Dse,  and  perhaps  persuade  a  raw  Squire,  by  it,  to  keep  his 
Money  in  his  Pocket;  and  if,  upon  this  account,  I  should  incur  the 


ARBUTHNOT.  51 

Clamours  of  the  Sharpers,  I  do   not  m^^ch  regard  it,  since  they   are 
a  sort  of  People  the  World  is  not  bound  to  provide  for 

...It  is  impossible  for  a  Die,  with  snch  determin'd  force  and  di- 
rection, not  to  fall  on  such  a  determin'd  side,  and  therefore  I  call  that 
Chance  which  is  nothing  but  want  of  Art ; 

The  Reader  may  here  observe  the  Force  of  Numbers,  which  can 
be  successfully  applied,  even  to  those  things,  which  one  would  imagine 
are  subject  to  no  Rules.  There  are  very  few  things  which  we  know, 
which  are  not  capable  of  Ijeing  reduc'd  to  a  Mathematical  Reasoning; 
and  when  they  cannot,  it's  a  sign  our  Knowledge  of  them  is  very  small 
and  confus'd;  and  where  a  mathematical  reasoning  can  be  had,  it's  as 
great  folly  to  make  use  of  any  other,  as  to  grope  for  a  thing  in  the 
dark,  when  you  have  a  Candle  standing  by  you.  I  believe  the  Cal- 
culation of  the  Quantity  of  Probability  might  be  improved  to  a  very 
useful  and  pleasant  Speculation,  and  applied  to  a  great  many  Events 
which   are  accidental,  besides  those  of  Games ; 

...There  is  likewise  a  Calculation  of  the  Quantity  of  Probability 
founded  on  Experience,  to  be  made  use  of  in  Wagers  about  any  thing; 
it  is  odds,  if  a  Woman  is  with  Child,  but  it  shall  be  a  Boy;  and  if 
you  would  know  the  just  odds,  you  must  consider  the  Proportion  in 
the  Bills  that  the  Males  bear  to  the  Females:  The  Yearlv  Bills  of 
Mortality  are  observed  to  bear  such  Proportion  to  the  live  People  as 
1  to  30,  or  2Q;  therefore  it  is  an  even  Wager,  that  one  out  of  thir- 
teen dies  within  a  Year  (which  may  be  a  good  reason,  tho'  not  the 
true,  of  that  foolish  piece  of  Superstition),  because,  at  this  rate,  if  1 
out  of  26  dies,  you  are  no  loser.  It  is  but  1  to  18  if  you  meet  a 
Parson  in  the  Street,  that  he  proves  to  be  a  Non-Juror,  because  there 
is  but  1  of  36  that  are  such. 

83.  Pages  1  to  25  contain  a  translation  of  Huygens's  treatise 
including  the  five  problems  which  he  left  unsolved.  Respecting 
these  our  author  says 

The  Calculus  of  the  preceding  Problems  is  left  out  by  Mons.  Huy- 
gens,  on  purpose  that  the  ingenious  Reader  may  have  the  satisfiiction  of 
applying  the  former  method  himself;  it  is  in  most  of  them  more  labo- 
rious than  difficult :  for  Example,  I  have  pitch'd  upon  the  second  and 
third,  because  the  rest  can  be  solv'd  after  the  same  Method. 

Our  author  solves  the  second  problem  in  the  first  of  the 
three  senses  which  it  may  bear  according  to  the  Ars  Conjectandi, 

4—2 


52  ARBUTHNOT. 

and  he  arrives  at  the  same  result  as  James  Bernoulli  on  page  58 
of  the  Ars  Conjectandi.     Our  author  adds, 

I  have  suppos'd  here  the  Sense  of  the  Problem  to  be,  that  when  any- 
one chus'd  a  Counter,  he  did  not  diminish  their  number;  but  if  he 
miss'd  of  a  white  one,  put  it  in  again,  and  left  an  equal  hazard  to  him 

who  had  the  following  choice;  for  if  it  be  otherwise  suppos'd,  ^'s  share 

55  9 

will  be  Y9^ »  which  is  less  than  Yq  • 

55 

This  result  ^-^  however  is  wrong  in  either  of  the   other  two 

senses  which  James  Bernoulli  ascribes  to  the  problem,  for  which  he 

77         101 
obtains  j^  and  z-^  respectively  as  the  results ;  see  Art.  35. 

84.  Then  follow  some  other  calculations  about  games.  We 
have  some  remarks  about  the  Boyal-Oak  Lottery  which  are  analo- 
gous to  those  made  on  the  Play  of  the  Royal  Oak  by  De  Moivre 
in  the  Preface  to  his  Doctrine  of  Chances. 

A  table  is  g^iven  of  the  number  of  various  throws  which  can  be 
made  with  three  dice.  Pages  84 — 39  are  taken  from  Pascal ;  they 
seem  introduced  abruptly,  and  they  give  very  little  that  had  not 
already  occurred  in  the  translation  of  Huygens's  treatise. 

85.  Our  author  touches  on  Whist ;  and  he  solves  two  problems 
about  the  situation  of  honours.  These  solutions  are  only  approxi- 
mate, as  he  does  not  distinguish  between  the  dealers  and  their 
adversaries.  And  he  also  solves  the  problem  of  comparing  the 
chances  of  two  sides,  one  of  which  is  at  eight  and  the  other  at 
nine;  the  same  remark  applies  to  this  solution.  He  makes  the 
chances  as  9  to  7;  De  Moivre  by  a  stricter  investigation  makes 
them  nearly  as  25  to  18.      See  Doctrine  of  Chances,  page  176. 

86.  Our  author  says  on  page  43, 

All  the  former  Cases  can  be  calculated  by  the  Theorems  laid  down 
by  Monsieur  Huygens;  but  Cases  more  compos'd  require  other  Prin- 
ciples; for  the  easy  and  ready  Computation  of  which,  I  shall  add  one 
Theorem  more,  demonstrated  after  Monsieur  Huygens's  method. 

The  theorem  is  :  "  if  I  have  p  Cliances  for  a,  q  Chances  for  h, 


ROBERTS.  53 

and  r  Chances  for  c,  then  my  hazard  is  worth ^J- — —  "     Our 

]_)^-  q  +  r 

author  demonstrates  this,  and  intimates  that  it  may  be  extended 

to  the  case  when  there  are  also  s  Chances  for  d,  &c. 

Our  author  then  considers  the  game  of  Hazard.  He  gives  an 
investigation  similar  to  that  in  De  Moivre,  and  leading  to  the 
same  results;  see  Doctrine  of  Chances,  page  IGO. 

87.  The  first  part  of  the  book  concludes  thus  : 

All  those  Problems  suppose  Chances,  which  are  in  an  equal  proba- 
bility to  happen;  if  it  should  be  suppos'd  otherwise,  there  will  arise 
variety  of  Cases  of  a  quite  different  nature,  which,  perhaps,  'twere  not 
unpleasant  to  consider :  I  sliall  add  one  Problem  of  that  kind,  leaving 
the  Solution  to  those  who  think  it  merits  their  pains. 

In  Parallel ipipedo  cujus  latera  sunt  ad  iuvicem  in  ratione  a,b,c: 
Invenire  quota  vice  quivis  suscipere  potest,  ut  datum  quodvis  planum, 
v.g.  aSjaciat. 

The  problem  was  aftersvards  discussed  by  Thomas  Simpson  ;  it 
is  Problem  xxvil,  of  his  Nature  and  Laius  of  CJiance. 

88.  It  will  be  convenient  to  postpone  an  account  of  the  second 
part  of  the  book  until  after  we  have  examined  the  works  of  De 
Moivre. 

89.  We  next  notice  An  Arithmetical  Paradox,  concerning  the 
Chances  of  Lotteries,  by  the  Honourable  Francis  Roberts,  Esq. ; 
Fellow  of  the  R  S. 

This  is  published  in  Vol.  xvii.  of  the  Philosophical  Trans- 
actions, 1693  ;  it  occupies  pages  677 — 681. 

Suppose  in  one  lottery  that  there  are  three  blanks,  and  three 
prizes  each  of  16  pence  ;  suppose  in  another  lottery  that  there  are 
four  blanks,  and  two  prizes  each  of  2  shilliugs.  Now  for  one 
drawing,  in  the  first  lottery  the  expectation  is  ^  of  16  pence,  and  in 
the  second  it  is  J  of  2  shillings  ;  so  that  it  is  8  pence  in  each  case. 
The  paradox  which  Roberts  finds  is  this ;  suppose  that  a  gamester 
pays  a  shilling  for  the  chance  in  one  of  these  lotteries ;  then 
although,  as  we  have  just  seen,  the  expectations  are  equal,  yet  the 
odds  against  him  are  3  to  1  in  the  first  lottery,  and  only  2  to  1  in 
the  second. 


Oi  CRAIG. 

The  paradox  is  made  by  Roberts  himself,  by  his  own  arbitrary 
definition  of  odds. 

Supposing  a  lottery  has  a  blanks  and  h  prizes,  and  let  each 
prize  be  r  shillings ;  and  suppose  a  gamester  gives  a  shilling  for 
one  drawing  in  the  lottery;  then  Roberts  says  the  odds  against 

a  1 

him  are  formed  by  the  product  of  j  ^^^  T  >  ^^^^  '^^)  "tl^®  ^^^^ 

are  as  a  to  Z>  (r  —  1).    This  is  entirely  arbitrary. 

The  mere  algebra  of  the  paper  is  quite  correct,  and  is  a  curious 
specimen  of  the  mode  of  work  of  the  day. 

The  author  is  doubtless  the  same  whose  name  is  spelt  Robartes 
in  De  Moivre's  Preface. 

90.  I  borrow  from  Lubbock  and  Drinkwater  an  account  of  a 
work  which  I  have  not  seen ;  it  is  given  on  their  page  45. 

It  is  not  necessary  to  do  more  than  mention  an  essay,  by  Craig,  on 
the  probability  of  testimony,  which  appeared  in  1699,  under  the  title 
of   "Theologi£e  Cliristianse  Principia  Mathematica."     This  attempt  to 
introduce  mathematical  language  and  reasoning  into  moral  subjects  can 
scarcely  be  read  with  seriousness ;  it  has  the  appearance  of  an  insane 
parody  of  Newton's  Principia,  which  then  engrossed  the  attention  of  the 
mathematical  world.     The  author  begins  by  stating  that  he  considers 
the  mind  as  a  movable,  and  arguments  as  so  many  moving  forces,  by 
which   a   certain   velocity   of  suspicion   is   produced,    &c.     He  proves 
gravely,  that  suspicions  of  any  history,  transmitted  through  the  given 
time  (cceteris  ^9aH62^s),  vary  in  the  duplicate  ratio  of  the  times  taken 
from  the  beginning  of  the  history,  with  much  more  of  the  same  kind 
with  respect  to  the  estimation  of  equable  pleasure,   uniformly  accele- 
rated pleasure,  pleasure  varying  as  any  power  of  the  time,  &c.  &c. 

It  is  stated  in  biographical  dictionaries  that  Craig's  work  was 
reprinted  at  Leipsic  in  1755,  with  a  refutation  by  J.  Daniel  Titius  ; 
and  that  some  Anwiadversiones  on  it  were  published  by  Peterson 
in  1701. 

Prevost  and  Lhuilier  notice  Craig's  work  in  a  memoir  published 
in  the  Memoires  de  VAcad... .Beiiin,  1797.  It  seems  that  Craig  con- 
cluded that  faith  in  the  Gospel  so  far  as  it  depended  on  oral  tra- 
dition expired  about  the  year  800,  and  that  so  far  as  it  depended 
on  written  tradition  it  would  expire  in  the  year  3150.     Peterson 


CEAIG.  55 

by  adopting  a  different  law  of  diminution  concluded  that  faith 
would  expire  in  1789. 

See  Montmort,  page  XXXVIII. ;  also  the  Athenceum  for  Nov,  7th, 
1863,  page  Gil. 

91.  A  Calctdation  of  the  C^'edihility  of  Human  Testimony  is 
contained  in  Vol.  xxi.  of  the  Philosophical  Transactions;  it  is  the 
volume  for  1699  :  the  essay  occupies  pages  359 — 365.  The  essay 
is  anonymous ;  Lubbock  and  Drinkwater  suggest  that  it  may  be 
by  Craig. 

The  views  do  not  agree  with  those  now  received. 

First  suppose  we  have  successive  witnesses.  Let  a  report  be 
transmitted  through  a  series  of  n  witnesses,  whose  credibilities  are 
Pi'  P^y-'Pn'  the  essay  takes  the  jDroduct  j^^j^g  '"Pn  ^s  representing 
the  resulting  probability. 

Next,  suppose  we  have  concurrent  witnesses.  Let  there  be  two 
witnesses ;  the  first  witness  is  supposed  to  leave  an  amount  of  un- 
certainty represented  by  1  —p{,  of  this  the  second  witness  removes 
the  fraction  p^,  and  therefore  leaves  the  fraction  (1  —p^  (1  —  p^  : 
thus  the  resulting  probability  is  ^  —  0- —  2\)  0-  ~2^2)-  Sii^^iiarly 
if  tliere  are  three  concurrent  testimonies  the  resulting  probability 
is  1  —  (1  —2\)  (1  —  i^a).  0-  —P^)  '}  ^^^^  s^  0^  ^^^'  '^  greater  number. 

The  theory  of  this  essay  is  adopted  in  the  article  Prohahilite 
of  the  original  French  Encyclopedie,  which  is  reproduced  in  the 
Encyclopedie  Methodique:  the  article  is  unsigned,  so  that  we  must 
apparently  ascribe  it  to  Diderot.  The  same  theory  is  adopted  by 
Bicquillcy  in  his  work  Bu  Calcul  des  Frohahilites. 


CHAPTER  VII. 

JAMES  BERNOULLI. 

92.  We  now  propose  to  give  an  account  of  the  Ars  Conjec- 
tandi  of  James  Bernoulli. 

James  Bernoulli  is  the  first  member  of  the  celebrated  family 
of  this  name  who  is  associated  with  the  history  of  Mathematics. 
He  was  born  27th  December,  1654,  and  died  16th  August,  1705. 
For  a  most  interesting  and  valuable  account  of  the  whole  family 
we  may  refer  to  the  essay  entitled  Die  Mathematiker  Bernoulli. . . 
von  Frof.  Dr.  Peter  Merian,  Basel,  1860. 

93.  Leibnitz  states  that  at  his  request  James  Bernoulli  studied 
the  subject.  Feu  Mr.  Bernoulli  a  cultive  cette  mati^re  sur  mes 
exhortations;  Leibnitii  Opera  Omnia,  ed.  Dutens,  Vol.  Vl.  part  1, 
page  217.  But  this  statement  is  not  confirmed  by  the  correspond- 
ence between  Leibnitz  and  James  Bernoulli,  to  which  we  have 
already  referred  in  Art.  59.  It  appears  from  this  correspondence 
that  James  Bernoulli  had  nearly  completed  his  work  before  he 
was  aware  that  Leibnitz  had  heard  any  thing  about  it.  Leibnitz 
says,  page  71, 

Audio  a  Te  doctrinam  de  aestimandis  probabilitatibus  (quam  ego 
magni  facio)  non  parum  esse  excultam.  Vellem  aliqiiis  varia  ludendi 
genera  (in  quibus  pulchra  hujus  doctrinae  specimina)  mathematice  trac- 
taret.  Id  simul  amoenum  et  utile  foret  nee  Te  aut  quocunque  gra- 
^issimo  Mathematico  indignum. 

James  Bernoulli  in  reply  says,  page  77, 

Scire  libenter  velim,  Amplissime  Vir,  a  quo  habeas,  quod  Doctrina 
de  probabilitatibus  aestimandis  a  me  excolatur.     Yerum  est  me  a  plu- 


JAMES   BERNOULLI.  57 

ribus  retro  annis  hujusmodi  speciilatlonibus  magnopere  delectari,  ut  vix 
piitem,  quemquani  plura  super  his  meclitatum  esse.  Animus  etiam 
erat,  Tractatum  quendam  conscribendi  de  hac  materia ;  sed  saepe  per 
integros  annos  seposui,  quia  naturalis  meus  torjoor,  quem  accessoria  vale- 
tiidinis  meae  infirmitas  immane  quantum  auxit,  facit  ut  aegerrime  ad 
Bcribendum  accedam ;  et  saepe  mihi  optarem  amanuensem,  qui  cogitata 
mea  leviter  sibi  indicata  plene  divinare,  scriptisque  consignare  posset. 
Absolvi  tamen  jam  maximam  Libri  partem,  sed  deest  adliuc  praecipua, 
qua  artis  conjee tandi  principia  etiam  ad  civilia,  moralia  et  oeconomia 
applicare  doceo... 

James  Bernoulli  then  proceeds  to  speak  of  the  celebrated 
theorem  which  is  now  called  by  his  name. 

Leibnitz  in  his  next  letter  brings  some  objections  against  the 
theorem ;  see  page  83 :  and  Bernoulli  replies ;  see  page  87.  Leib- 
nitz returns  to  the  subject;  see  page  9-i:  and  Bernoulli  briefly 
replies,  page  97, 

Quod  Yerisimilitudines  spectat,  et  earum  augmentum  pro  aucto  soil, 
observationum  numero,  res  omnino  se  habet  ut  scripsi,  et  certus  sum 
Tibi  placituram  demonstration  em,  cum  publicavero. 

94.  The  last  letter  from  James  Bernoulli  to  Leibnitz  is  dated 
3rd  June,  1705.  It  closes  in  a  most  painful  manner.  We  here  see 
him,  who  was  perhaps  the  most  famous  of  all  who  have  borne 
his  famous  name,  suffering  under  the  combined  sorrow  arising  from 
illness,  from  the  ingratitude  of  his  brother  John  who  had  been 
his  pupil,  and  from  the  unjust  suspicions  of  Leibnitz  who  may 
be  considered  to  have  been  his  master : 

Si  inimor  vere  narrat,  redibit  cei'te  frater  meus  Basileam,  non  tamen 
Graecam  (cum  ipse  sit  dva\<jidf3-r]Tos)  sed  meam  potius  stationem  (quara 
brevi  cum  vita  me  derelicturum,  forte  non  vane,  existimat)  occupatunis. 
De  iniquis  suspicionibus,  quibus  me  immerentem  onerasti  in  Tuis  pe- 
nultimis,  alias,  ubi  plus  otii  nactus  fuero.     Nimc  vale  et  fave  etc. 

95.  Tlie  Ars  Conjectandi  was  not  published  until  eight  years 
after  the  death  of  its  author.  The  volume  of  the  Hist,  de 
r  A  cad....  Pains  for  1705,  published  in  1706,  contains  Fontenelle's 
Eloge  of  James  Bernoulli.  Fontenelle  here  gave  a  brief  notice, 
derived  from  Hermann,  of  the  contents  of  the  Ars  Conjectandi 
then  unpublished.    A  brief  notice  is  also  give  in  another  Eloge  of 


58  JAMES   BERNOULLI. 

James  Bernoulli  wliicli  appeared  in  the  Journal  des  Bgavans 
for  1706:  this  notice  is  attributed  to  Saurin  by  Montmort;  see  his 
page  IV. 

References  to  the  work  of  James  Bernoulli  frequently  occur  in 
the  correspondence  between  Leibnitz  and  John  Bernoulli ;  see  the 
work  cited  in  Art.  59,  pages  367,  377,  836,  8i5,  847,  922,  923, 
925,  931. 

96.  The  A^^s  Conjectandi  was  published  in  1713.  A  preface 
of  two  pages  was  supplied  by  Nicolas  Bernoulli,  the  son  of  a 
brother  of  James  and  John.  It  appears  from  the  preface  that 
the  fourth  part  of  the  work  was  left  unfinished  by  its  author ;  the 
publishers  had  desired  that  the  work  should  be  finished  by  John 
Bernoulli,  but  the  numerous  engagements  of  this  mathematician 
had  been  an  obstacle.  It  was  then  proposed  to  devolve  the  task 
on  Nicolas  Bernoulli,  who  had  already  turned  his  attention  to 
the  Theory  of  Probability.  But  Nicolas  Bernoulli  did  not  con- 
sider himself  adequate  to  the  task;  and  by  his  advice  the  work 
was  finally  published  in  the  state  in  which  its  author  had  left  it; 
the  words  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli  are,  Suasor  itaque  fui,  ut  Tractatus 
iste  qui  maxima  ex  parte  jam  impressus  erat,  in  eodem  quo  eum 
Auctor  reliquit  statu  cum  publico  communicaretur. 

The  Ars  Conjectandi  is  not  contained  in  the  collected  edition 
of  James  Bernoulli's  works. 

97.  TYvqAvs  Conjectandi,  including  a  treatise  on  infinite  series, 
consists  of  306  small  quarto  pages  besides  the  title  leaf  and  the 
preface.  At  the  end  there  is  a  dissertation  in  French,  entitled 
Lettre  d  un  Amy,  sur  les  Parties  du  Jeu  de  Paume  which  occu- 
pies 35  additional  pages.  Montucla  speaks  of  this  letter  as  the 
work  of  an  anonymous  author ;  see  his  page  391 :  but  there  can 
be  no  doubt  that  it  is  due  to  James  Bernoulli,  for  to  him  Nicolas 
Bernoulli  assigns  it  in  the  preface  to  the  J.rs  Conjectandi,  and 
in  his  correspondence  with  Montmort.     See  Montmort,  page  333. 

98.  The  Ars  Conjectandi  is  divided  into  four  parts.  The 
first  part  consists  of  a  reprint  of  the  treatise  of  Huygens  De  Ra- 
tiociniis  in  Ludo  Alece,  accompanied  with  a  commentary  by  James 
Bernoulli.  The  second  part  is  devoted  to  the  theory  of  permu- 
tations and  combinations.     The  third  part  consists  of  the  solution 


JAMES   BEENOULLT.  59 

of  various  problems  relating  to  games  of  chance.  The  fourth  part 
proposed  to  apply  the  Theory  of  Probability  to  questions  of  interest 
in  morals  and  economical  science. 

We  may  observe  that  instead  of  the  ordinary  symbol  of 
equality,  =  James  Bernoulli  uses  x,  which  Wallis  ascribes  to  Des 
Cartes;  see  Walliss  Algebra,  1693,  page  138. 

99.  A  French  translation  of  the  first  part  of  the  Ars  Con- 
jectandi   was   published   in   1801,   under  the  title    of  LArt    de 

Conjecturer,  Tradidt  du  Latin  de  Jacques  Bernoulli;  Avec  des 
Observations,  Eclair cissemens  et  Additions.  Far  L.  G.  F.  Vastel,... 
Caen.  1801. 

The  second  part  of  the  Ars  Conjectandi  is  included  in  the 
volume  of  reprints  which  we  have  cited  in  Art.  47;  Maseres  in 
the  same  volume  gave  an  English  translation  of  this  part. 

100.  The  first  part  of  the  Ars  Conjectandi  occupies  pages 
1 — 71 ;  with  respect  to  this  part  we  may  observe  that  the  com- 
mentary by  James  Bernoulli  is  of  more  value  than  the  original 
treatise  by  Huygens.  The  commentary  supplies  other  proofs  of 
the  fundamental  propositions  and  other  investigations  of  the  pro- 
blems; also  in  some  cases  it  extends  them.  We  will  notice  the 
most  important  additions  made  by  James  Bernoulli. 

101.  In  the  Problem  of  Points  with  two  players,  James 
Bernoulli  gives  a  table  which  furnishes  the  chances  of  the  two 
players  when  one  of  them  wants  any  number  of  points  not 
exceeding  nine,  and  the  other  wants  any  number  of  points  not 
exceeding  seven ;  and,  as  he  remarks,  this  table  may  be  j^rolonged 
to  any  extent;  see  his  page  16. 

102.  James  Bernoulli  gives  a  long  note  on  the  subject  of 
the  various  throws  which  can  be  made  with  two  or  more  dice, 
and  the  number  of  cases  favourable  to  each  throw.  And  we  may 
especially  remark  that  he  constructs  a  large  table  which  is  equi- 
valent to  the  theorem  we  now  express  thus :  the  number  of  ways 
in  which  ni  can  be  obtained  by  throwing  n  dice  is  equal  to  the 
co-efficient  of  ^'"  in  the  development  of  {x  +  x^  -{- x^  -\- x^  ^  x°  -\-  x^ 
in  a  series  of  powers  of  x.     See  his  page  21;. 


60  JAMES   BERNOULLI. 

103.  The  tenth  problem  is  to  find  in  how  many  trials  one 
may  undertake  to  throw  a  six  with  a  common  die.  James  Bernoulli 
gives  a  note  in  reply  to  an  objection  which  he  suggests  might 
be  urged  against  the  result;  the  reply  is  perhaps  only  intended 
as  a  popular  illustration :  it  has  been  criticized  by  Prevost  in  the 
NoiLveaux  Memoir  es  de  FA  cad....  Berlin  for  1781. 

104.  James  Bernoulli  gives  the  general   expression  for  the 

chance  of  succeeding  m  times  at  least  in  n  trials,  when  the  chance 

of  success  in  a  single  trial  is  known.     Let  the  chances  of  success 

b  c 

and  failure  in  a  single  trial  be  -  and  -  respectively:   then  the 

required  chance  consists  of  the  terms  of  the  expansion  of     -  +  — ) 

from  ( -  j    to  the  term  which  involves     -  j    [  -  J     ,  both  inclusive. 

This  formula  involves  a  solution  of  the  Problem  of  Points  for 
two  players  of  unequal  skill;  but  James  Bernoulli  does  not  ex- 
plicitly make  the  application. 

105.  James  Bernoulli  solves  four  of  the  five  problems  which 
Huygens  had  placed  at  the  end  of  his  treatise ;  the  solution  of  the 
fourth  problem  he  postpones  to  the  third  part  of  his  book  as  it 
depends  on  combinations. 

106.  Perhaps  however  the  most  valuable  contribution  to  the 
subject  which  this  part  of  the  work  contains  is  a  method  of  solving 
problems  in  chances  which  James  Bernoulli  speaks  of  as  his  own, 
and  which  he  frequently  uses.  We  will  give  his  solution  of  the 
problem  which  forms  the  fourteenth  proposition  of  the  treatise 
of  Huygens :  we  have  already  given  the  solution  of  Huygens  him- 
self; see  Art.  34. 

Instead  of  two  players  conceive  an  infinite  number  of  players 
each  of  whom  is  to  have  one  throw  in  turn.  The  game  is  to 
end  as  soon  as  a  player  whose  turn  is  denoted  by  an  odd  number 
throws  a  six,  or  a  player  whose  turn  is  denoted  by  an  even  number 
throws  a  seven,  and  such  player  is  to  receive  the  whole  sum  at 
stake.  Let  h  denote  the  number  of  ways  in  which  six  can  be 
thrown,  c  the  number  of  ways  in  which  six  can  fail;  so  that  6  =  5, 


JAMES  BERNOULLI.  61 

and  c  =  31 ;  let  e  denote  the  number  of  ways  in  which  seven  can 
be  thrown,  and  /the  number  of  ways  in  which  seven  can  fail,  so 
that  e  =  6,  and  /=  30 ;  and  let  a  =  6  4-  c  =  e  +/ 

Now  consider  the  expectations  of  the  different  players ;  they 
are  as  follows: 


I. 

II. 

III. 

IV. 

V. 

YI. 

YIL 

YIIL... 

h 

a' 

ce 

2  > 

a 

hcf 
a'' 

e'er 

For  it  is  obvious  that  -  expresses  the  expectation  of  the  first 

player.     In  order  that  the  second  player  may  win,  the  first  throw 

must  fail  and  the  second  throw  must  succeed ;  that  is  there  are  ce 

ce 
favourable  cases  out  of  o^  cases,  so  the  expectation  is   -2 .      In 

order  that  the  third  player  may  win,  the  first  throw  must  fail, 

the  second  throw  must  fail,  and  the  third  throw  must  succeed; 

that  is  there  are  cfh  favourable  cases  out  of  a^  cases,  so  the  ex- 

Icf 
pectation  is    —  .      And  so  on  for  the  other  players.     Now  let  a 
a 

single  player.  A,  be  substituted  in  our  mind  in  the  place  of  the 

first,  third,  fifth,...;  and  a  single  player,  B,  in  the  place  of  the 

second,  fourth,  sixth....  We  thus  arrive  at  the  problem  proposed 

by  Huygens,  and  the  expectations  of  A  and  B  are  given  by  two 

infinite  geometrical  progressions.     By  summing  these  progressions 

we  find  that  ^'s  expectation  is    -3 — -,  and  5's  expectation  is 

CB 

;   the  proportion  is  that  of  30  to  81,  which  agrees  with 


the  result  in  Art.  31. 

107.  The  last  of  the  five  problems  which  Huygens  left  to  be 
solved  is  the  most  remarkable  of  all ;  see  Art.  35.  It  is  the  first 
example  on  the  Duration  of  Play,  a  subject  which  afterwards 
exercised  the  highest  powers  of  De  Moi\Te,  Lagrange,  and  Laplace. 
James  Bernoulli  solved  the  problem,  and  added,  without  a  demon- 
stration, the  result  for  a  more  general  problem  of  which  that  of 
Huygens  was   a  particular  case;    see  Ars  Conjectandi  page  71. 


62  JAMES   BERNOULLI. 

Suppose  A  to  have  m  counters,  and  B  to  have  n  counters ;  let  their 
chances  of  winning  in  a  single  game  be  as  a  to  6 ;  the  loser  in  each 
game  is  to  give  a  counter  to  his  adversary :  required  the  chance  of 
each  player  for  winning  all  the  counters  of  his  adversary.  In  the 
case  taken  by  Huygens  m  and  n  were  equal. 

It  will  be  convenient  to  give  the  modern  form  of  solution  of 
the  problem. 

Let  u^  denote  J.'s  chance  of  winning  all  his  adversary's  count- 
ers when  he  has  himself  w  counters.  In  the  next  game  A  must 
either  win  or  lose  a  counter;  his  chances  for  these  two  contin- 
gencies are  r  and  t-  respectively:    and  then  his  chances 

of  winning  all  his  adversary's  counters  are  u^_^_^  and  u^_^  respectively. 

Hence 

_     a  h 

This  equation  is  thus  obtained  in  the  manner  exemplified  by 
Huygens  in  his  fourteenth  proposition;    see  Art.  34. 

The  equation  in  Finite  Differences  may  be  solved  in  the  or- 
dinary way;  thus  we  shall  obtain 

where  C^  and  C^  are  arbitrary  constants.  To  determine  these 
constants  we  observe "  that  ^'s  chance  is  zero  when  he  has  no 
counters,  and  that  it  is  unity  when  he  has  all  the  counters.  Thus 
u^  is  equal  to  0  when  x  is  0,  and  is  equal  to  1  when  x  is  m  +  n. 
Hence  we  have 

0=0.+ a„    1  =  0.+ c,g) 


«x 


«!+n 


therefore  ^i  —  ~  ^2~ 


m+n 1  m+n   ' 


Hence  u^  = 


^m+n  _  ^m+n-:c  J^, 


X  rn-^n  J  vi+n 


To  determine  ^'s  chance  at  the  beginning  of  the  game  we 
must  put  x  =  m;  thus  we  obtain 


7/       = 


JAMES   BERXOULLI.  63 

In  precisely  tlie  same  manner  we  may  find  jS's  chance  at  any 

stage  of  the  game ;  and  his  chance  at  the  beginning  of  the  game 

will  be 

h""  (g^  -  If) 

It  will  be  observed  that  the  sum  of  the  chances  of  A  and  B  at 
the  beginning  of  the  game  is  unitif.  The  interpretation  of  this 
result  is  that  one  or  other  of  the  players  must  eventually  win 
all  the  counters;  that  is,  the  play  must  terminate.  This  might 
have  been  expected,  but  was  not  assumed  in  the  investigation. 

The  formula  which  James  Bernoulli  here  gives  will  next  come 
before  us  in  the  correspondence  between  Nicolas  Bernoulli  and 
Montmort;  it  was  however  first  published  by  De  Moi\Te  in  his 
De  Mensiira  Soiiis,  Problem  ix.,  where  it  is  also  demonstrated. 

108.  We  may  observe  that  Bernoulli  seems  to  have  found, 
as  most  who  have  studied  the  subject  of  chances  have  also  found, 
that  it  was  extremely  easy  to  fall  into  mistakes,  especially  by 
attempting  to  reason  without  strict  calculation.  Thus,  on  his 
page  15,  he  points  out  a  mistake  into  which  it  would  have  been 
easy  to  fall,  nisi  nos  calculus  aliud  clocuisset     He  adds, 

Qao  ipso  proin  monemiir,  ut  cauti  siraiis  in  jiidicando,  'nee  ratio- 
cinia  nostra  super  qiiacunque  statim  aiialogia  in  rebus  deprehensji  fun- 
dare  suescamus;  quod  ipsum  tamen  etiam  ab  iis,  qui  vel  maxinie  sapere 
videntur,  nimis  frequenter  fieri  solet. 

Again,  on  his  page  27, 

Quae  quideiu  eum  in  finem  hie  adduce,  ut  palam  fiat,  quam  parum 
fideudum  sit  ejusmodi  ratiociniis,  qu?e  corticem  tantuiu  attingunt,  nee 
in  ipsam  rei  naturam  altius  penetrant;  tametsi  in  toto  vitse  usu  etiam. 
apud  sapientissimos  quosque  nihil  sit  frequentius. 

Again,  on  his  page  29,  he  refers  to  the  difficulty  which  Pascal 
says  had  been  felt  by  M.  de  *  *  *  *,  whom  James  Bernoulli  calls 
Anonymus  quidam  coetera  subacti  judicii  Yir,  sed  Geometriae 
expers.  .  James  Bernoulli  adds, 

Hac  enim  qui  imbuti  sunt,  ejusmodi  erai'Tto^avetai  minime  moran- 
tur,  probe  conscii  dari  innumera,  qua3  admoto  calculo  aliter  se  habere 
comperiuntur,  quam  initio  apparebaut;  ideoque  sedulb  cavent,  juxta  id 
quod  semel  iterumque  monui,  ne  quicquam  analogiis  temere  tribuant. 


64  JA^IES   BERNOULLI. 

109.  The  second  part  of  the  Ars  Conjectandi  occupies  pages 
72 — ]  87  :  it  contains  the  doctrine  of  Permutations  and  Combina- 
tions. James  Bernoulli  says  that  others  have  treated  this  subject 
before  him,  and  especially  Schooten,  Leibnitz,  Wallis  and  Prestet ; 
and  so  he  intimates  that  his  matter  is  not  entirely  new.  He  con- 
tinues thus,  page  73, 

...tametsi  qusedam  non  contemnenda  de  nostro  adjecimus,  inprimis 
demonstrationem  generalem  et  facilem  proprietatis  numerorum  figura- 
torum,  cui  csetera  pleraque  innituntur,  et  quam  nemo  quod  sciam  ante 
nos  dedit  eruitve. 

110.  James  Bernoulli  begins  by  treating  on  permutations; 
he  proves  the  ordinary  rule  for  finding  the  number  of  permuta- 
tions of  a  set  of  things  taken  all  together,  when  there  are  no 
repetitions  among  the  set  of  things  and  also  when  there  are.  He 
gives  a  full  analysis  of  the  number  of  arrangements  of  the  verse 
Tot  tibi  sunt  dotes,  Virgo,  quot  sidera  coeli ;  see  Art.  40.  He  then 
considers  combinations ;  and  first  he  finds  the  total  number  of  ways 
in  which  a  set  of  things  can  be  taken,  by  taking  them  one  at  a 
time,  two  at  a  time,  three  at  a  time, ...He  then  proceeds  to  find 
what  we  should  call  the  number  of  combinations  of  n  things  taken 
r  at  a  time ;  and  here  is  the  part  of  the  subject  in  which  he 
added  most  to  the  results  obtained  by  his  predecessors.  He 
gives  a  figure  which  is  substantially  the  same  as  Pascal's  Arith- 
metical Triangle;  and  he  arrives  at  two  results,  one  of  which 
is  the  well-known  form  for  the  nth.  term  of  the  rth  order  of 
figurate  numbers,  and  the  other  is  the  formula  for  the  sum  of 
a  given  number  of  terms  of  the  series  of  figurate  numbers  of  a 
given  order ;  these  results  are  expressed  definitely  in  the  modern 
notation  as  we  now  have  them  in  works  on  Algebra.  The  mode  of 
proof  is  more  laborious,  as  might  be  expected.  Pascal  as  we  have 
seen  in  Arts.  22  and  41,  employed  without  any  scruple,  and  indeed 
rather  with  approbation,  the  method  of  induction  :  James  Bernoulli 
however  says,  page  95,...  modus  demonstrandi  per  inductionem 
parum  scientificus  est. 

James  Bernoulli  names  his  predecessors  in  investigations  on 
figurate  numbers  in  the  following  terms  on  his  page  95 : 

Multi,  ut  hoc  in  transitu  notemus,  numerorum  figuratorum  contem- 


JAMES    BERNOULLI.  65 

plafcionibua  vacarunt  (quos  inter  Faulliaberus  et  Remmelini  TJlmenEes, 
Wallisius,  Mercator  in  Logarithmotechnia,  Prestetus,  aliique)... 

111.  We  may  notice  that  James  Bernoulli  gives  incidentally 
on  his  page  89  a  demonstration  of  the  Binomial  Theorem  for  the 
case  of  a  positive  integral  exponent.  Maseres  considers  this  to 
be  the  first  demonstration  that  appeared ;  see  page  283  of  the 
work  cited  in  Ai't.  47. 

112.  From  the  summation  of  a  series  of  figurate  numbers 
James  Bernoulli  proceeds  to  derive  the  summation  of  the  powers 
of  the  natural  numbers.  He  exhibits  definitely  2?i,  Sn^  2n^... 
up  to  Xw^" ;  he  uses  the  sj^mbol  /  where  we  in  modern  books  use  S. 
He  then  extends  his  results  by  induction  without  demonstration, 
and  introduces  for  the  first  time  into  Analysis  the  coefficients  since 
so  famous  as  the  numbers  of  Bernoulli.     His  general  formula  is  that 

^    ,      n'"-'       n'     c    .    ^_,      c(c-l)(c-2)  J,  ,_^ 

c(c-l)(c-2)(c-3)(o-4)        _, 
^  2.3.4.5.6 

c(c-.l)(o-2)(c-3)(c-4)(c-5)(c~6) 
"^  2.3.4.5.6.7.8  '^'" 

where  ^  =  6  '  ^  =  "  SO  '  ^  =  A' ^  =  - i'  - 

He  gives  the  numerical  value  of  the  sum  of  the  tenth  powers 
of  the  first  thousand  natural  numbers ;  the  result  is  a  number 
with  thirty-two  figures.     He  adds,  on  his  page  98, 

E  quibus  apparet,  quam  inutilis  censenda  sit  opera  Jsmaelis  Bul- 
lialdi,  quam  conscribendo  tarn  spisso  volumini  Arithmeticae  sufe  Infijii- 
torum  impendit,  ubi  niliil  prgestitit  aliud,  quam  ut  primarum  tantum 
sex  potestatum  summas  (partem  ejus  quod  unica  nos  consecuti  sumus 
pagina)  immense  labore  demonstratas  exhiberet. 

For  some  account  of  Bulliald's  sjnssum  volumen,  see  Wallis's 
Algebra,  Chap.  LXXX. 

113.  James  Bernoulli  gives  in  his  fourth  Chapter  the  rule 
now  well  known  for  the  number  of  the  combinations  of  ti  thiners 


66  JAMES  BERNOULLI. 

taken  c  at  a  time.  He  also  draws  various  simple  inferences  from 
the  rule.  He  digresses  from  the  subject  of  this  part  of  his  book  to 
resume  the  discussion  of  the  Problem  of  Points  ;  see  his  page  107. 
He  gives  two  methods  of  treating  the  problem  by  the  aid  of 
the  theory  of  combinations.  The  first  method  shews  how  the 
table  which  he  had  exhibited  in  the  first  part  of  the  A7'S  Con- 
jectandi  might  be  continued  and  the  law  of  its  terms  expressed; 
the  table  is  a  statement  of  the  chances  of  A  and  B  for  winning 
the  game  when  each  of  them  wants  an  assigned  number  of  points. 
Pascal  had  himself  given  such  a  table  for  a  game  of  six  points ; 
an  extension  of  the  table  is  given  on  page  16  of  the  Ars  Con- 
jectandi,  and  now  James  Bernoulli  investigates  general  expressions 
for  the  component  numbers  of  the  table.  From  his  investigation 
he  derives  the  result  which  Pascal  gave  for  the  case  in  which  one 
player  wants  one  point  more  than  the  other  player.  James  Ber- 
noulli concludes  this  investigation  thus ;  Ipsa  solutio  Pascaliana, 
quae  Auctori  suo  tantopere  arrisit. 

James  Bernoulli's  other  solution  of  the  Problem  of  Points  is 
much  more  simple  and  direct,  for  here  he  does  make  the  application 
to  which  we  alluded  in  Art.  101^  Suppose  that  A  wants  m  points 
and  B  wants  7i  points ;  then  the  game  will  certainly  be  decided  in 
m  +  n  —  1  trials.  As  in  each  trial  A  and  B  have  equal  chances 
of  success  the  whole  number  of  possible  cases  is  2"'"^""\  And 
A  wins  the  game  if  B  gains  no  point,  or  if  B  gains  just  one  point, 
or  just  two  points,...  or  any  number  up  to  w  —  1  inclusive.  Thus 
the  number  of  cases  favourable  to  A  is 

!  +  ;.  +  _-_ + ^ +  ...  + ^^^ ^ 

where  //<  =  m  -f  w  —  1 . 

Pascal  had  in  effect  advanced  as  far  as  this;  see  Art.  23:  but 
the  formula  is  more  convenient  than  the  Arithmetical  Triangle. 

114.  In  his  fifth  Chapter  James  Bernoulli  considers  another 
question  of  combinations,  namely  that  which  in  modern  treatises  is 
enunciated  thus  :  to  find  the  number  of  homogeneous  products  of 
the  r^^  degree  which  can  be  formed  of  n  symbols.  In  his  sixth 
Chapter  he  continues  this  subject,  and  makes  a  slight  reference  to 


JAMES   BERNOULLI.  67 

the  doctrine  of  the  number  of  divisors  of  a  given  number;  for 
more  information  he  refers  to  the  works  of  Schooten  and  WaUis, 
which  we  have  already  examined ;  see  Arts.  42,  47. 

115.  In  his  seventh  Chapter  James  Bernoulli  gives  the  for- 
mula for  what  we  now  call  the  number  of  permutations  of  n  things 
taken  c  at  a  time.  In  the  remainder  of  this  part  of  his  book  he 
discusses  some  other  questions  relating  to  permutations  and  com- 
binations, and  illustrates  his  theory  by  examples. 

116.  The  third  part  of  the  Ars  Conjectandi  occupies  pages 
138 — 209;  it  consists  of  twenty-four  problems  which  are  to  illus- 
trate the  theory  that  has  gone  before  in  the  book.  James  Ber- 
noulli gives  only  a  few  lines  of  introduction,  and  then  proceeds  to 
the  problems,  which  he  says, 

...nullo  fere  habito  selectu,  prout  in  adversariis  reperi,  proponam,  prre- 
niissis  etiam  vel  intersj)ersis  nonnuUis  facilioribus,  et  in  quibua  nidlus 
combiiiationum  usus  apparet. 

117.  The  fourteenth  problem  deserves  some  notice.  There 
are  two  cases  in  it,  but  it  will  be  sufficient  to  consider  one  of 
them.  A  is  to  throw  a  die,  and  then  to  repeat  his  throw  as  many 
times  as  the  number  thrown  the  first  time.  A  is  to  have  the 
whole  stake  if  the  sum  of  the  numbers  given  by  the  latter  set  of 
throws  exceeds  12;  he  is  to  have  half  the  stake  if  the  sum  is 
equal  to  12;  and  he  is  to  have  nothing  if  the  sum  is  less  than 
12.     Required  the  value  of  his  expectation.     It  is  found  to  be 

^Y^^rr ,   Avliich  is  rather  less  than  ^ .      After  giving  the  connect 

solution  James  Bernoulli  gives  another  which  is  plausible  but 
false,  in  order,  as  he  says,  to  impress  on  his  readers  the  necessity 
of  caution  in  these  discussions.     The  following  is  the  false  solution. 

A  has  a  chance  equal  to  -x  of  throwing  an  ace  at  his  first  trial; 

in  this  case  he  has  only  one  throw  for  the  stake,  and  that  throw 
may  give  him  with  equal  probabihty  any  number  between  1  and  6 

inclusive,  so  that  we  may  take  ^  (1  +  2  +  34-44-5+6),  that  is 

31,  for  his  mean  throw.     We  may  observe  that  3^  is  the  Arith- 

5—2 


68  JAiyiES   BERNOULLI. 

metical  mean  between  1  and  6.     Again  A  has  a  chance  equal  to  - 

of  throwing  a  two  at  his  first  trial ;  in  this  case  he  has  two  throws 
for  the  stake,  and  these  two  throws  may  give  him  any  number 
between  2  and  12  inclusive;  and  the  probability  of  the  number 
2  is  the  same  as  that  of  12,  the  probability  of  3  is  the  same  as 

that  of  11,  and  so  on;  hence  as  before  we  may  take  ^  (2  +  12), 

that  is  7,  for  his  mean  throw.  In  a  similar  way  if  three,  four, 
five,  or  six  be  thrown  at  the  first  trial,  the  corresponding  means 
of  the  numbers  in  the  throws  for  the  stake  will  be  respectively 
lOi,  14i,  17^,  and  21.     Hence  the  mean  of  all  the  numbers  is 

^  m  +  7  +  lOi  +  1-i  +  I7i  +  21],  that  is  121; 

and  as  this  number  is  greater  than  12  it  might  appear  that  the 
odds  are  in  favour  of  A. 

A  false  solution  of  a  problem  will  generally  appear  more  plau- 
sible to  a  person  who  has  originally  been  deceived  by  it  than  to 
another  person  who  has  not  seen  it  until  after  he  has  studied  the 
accurate  solution.  To  some  persons  James  Bernoulli's  false  solu- 
tion 'would  appear  simply  false  and  not  plausible;  it  leaves  the 
problem  proposed  and  substitutes  another  which  is  entirely  differ- 
ent. This  may  be  easily  seen  by  taking  a  simple  example. 
Suppose  that  A  instead  of  an  equal  chance  for  any  number  of 
throws  between  one  and  six  inclusive,  is  restricted  to  one  or  six 
throws,  and  that  each  of  these  two  cases  is  equally"  likely.     Then, 

as   before,    we   may  take  -^  (8 J  +  21],  that  is  12J   as  the  mean 

throw.  But  it  is  obvious  that  the  odds  are  against  him;  for  if 
he  has  only  one  throw  he  cannot  obtain  12,  and  if  he  has  six 
throws  he  will  not  necessarily  obtain  12.  The  question  is  not 
what  is  the  mean  number  he  will  obtain,  but  how  many  throws 
will  give  him  12  or  more,  and  how  many  will  give  him  less  than  12. 
James  Bernoulli  seems  not  to  have  been  able  to  make  out 
more  than  that  the  second  solution  must  be  false  because  the  first 
is  unassailable;  for  after  saying  that  from  the  second  solution  we 
might  suppose  the  odds    to  be  in  fiiv^our  of  A,  he  adds,  Hujus 


JAMES   BERNOULLI.  G9 

aiitem  contrarium  ex  priore  solutione,  quae  sua  luce  radiat,  ap- 
paret;  ... 

The  problem  has  been  since  considered  by  Mallet  and  by  Fuss, 
who  agree  with  James  Bernoulli  in  admitting  the  plausibility  of 
the  false  solution. 

118.  James  Bernoulli  examines  in  detail  some  of  the  games  of 
chance  which  were  popular  in  his  day.  Thus  on  pages  167  and  168 
he  takes  the  game  called  Cinq  et  neuf.  He  takes  on  pages  16.0 — 174* 
a  game  which  had  been  brought  to  his  notice  by  a  stroller  at 
fairs.  According  to  James  Bernoulli  the  chances  were  against  the 
stroller,  and  so  as  he  says,  istumque  proin  hoc  alese  genere,  ni 
praemia  minuat,  non  multum  lucrari  posse.  We  might  desire  to 
know  more  of  the  stroller  who  thus  supplied  the  occasion  of  an 
elaborate  discussion  to  James  Bernoulli,  and  who  offered  to  the 
public  the  amusement  of  gambling  on  terms  unfavourable  to 
himself. 

James  Bernoulli  then  proceeds  to  a  game  called  Trijaques. 
He  considers  that,  it  is  of  great  importance  for  a  placer  to  main- 
tain a  serene  composure  even  if  the  cards  are  unfavourable,  and 
that  a  previous  calculation  of  the  chances  of  the  game  will  assist 
in  securing  the  requisite  command  of  countenance  and  temper. 
As  James  Bernoulli  speaks  immediately  afterwards  of  what  he 
had  himself  formerl}^  often  observed  in  the  game,  we  may  perhaps 
infer  that  Trijaques  had  once  been  a  favourite  amusement  with 
him. 

119.  The  nineteenth  problem  is  thus  enunciated, 

In  quolibet  Alese  genere,  si  ludi  Oeconomus  sen  Dispensator  {le 
Banquier  du  Jeu)  nonnihil  habeat  praerogativse  in  eo  consistentis,  ut  paulo 
major  sit  casuiim  nnmeriis  quibus  vincit  quam  quibus  perdit;  et  major 
simul  casuum  numerus,  quibus  in  officio  Oeconomi  ])ro  ludo  sequenti 
confirmutur,  quam  quibus  ceconomia  in  collusorem  transfertur.  Quanitur, 
quanti  privilegium  hoc  Oeconomi  sit  lestimandum  ? 

The  problem  is  chiefly  remarkable  from  the  fact  that  James 
Bernoulli  candidly  records  two  false  solutions  which  occuiTed  to 
him  before  he  obtained  the  true  solution. 

120.  The  twenty-first  problem  relates  to  the  game  of  Bassette; 


70  JAMES  BERNOULLI. 

James  Bernoulli  devotes  eiglit  pages  to  it,  his  object  being  to 
estimate  the  advantage  of  the  banker  at  the  game.     See  Art.  74>. 

The  last  three  problems  which  James  Bernoulli  discusses 
arose  from  his  observing  that  a  certain  stroller,  in  order  to  entice 
persons  to  play  with  him,  offered  them  among  the  conditions  of 
the  game  one  which  was  apparently  to  their  advantage,  but 
which  on  investigation  was  shewn  to  be  really  pernicious ;  see  his 
pages  208,  209. 

121.  The  fourth  part  of  the  Ay^s  Conjectandi  occupies  pages 
210 — 239 ;  it  is  entitled  Pars  Quai'ta,  tradens  usum  et  apj^licatio- 
nem  prwcedentis  Doctrince  in  Civilibus,  Moralihus  et  Oeconomicis.  It 
was  unfortunately  left  incomplete  by  the  author;  but  nevertheless 
it  may  be  considered  the  most  important  part  of  the  whole  work. 
It  is  divided  into  five  Chapters,  of  which  we  will  give  the  titles. 

I.  Prceliminaria  qucedam  de  Certitudine,  Prohahilitate,  Neces- 
sitate, et  Contingentia  Rerum. 

II.  De  Scieniia  et  Conjectura.  De  Arte  Conjectandi.  De 
Argumentis  Conjecturanmi,  Axiomata  quwdam  generalia  hue 
pertinentia. 

III.  De  variis  argiimentorum  generihus,  et  quomodo  eorum 
pondera  wstimentur  ad  supputandas  rerum  prohahilitates. 

lY.  De  duplici  Modo  investigandi  mimeros  casiium.  Quid 
sentiendum  de  illo,  qui  instituitur  per  experimenta.  Prohlenia 
singulare  eani  in  rem  propositum,  &c. 

V.     Solutio  Prohlematis  prcecedentis. 

122.  We  will  briefly  notice  the  results  of  James  Bernoulli 
as  to  the  probability  of  arguments.  He  distinguishes  arguments 
into  two  kinds,  pure  and  mixed.  He  says,  Pura  voco,  quoe  in  qui- 
busdam  casibus  ita  rem  probant,  ut  in  aliis  nihil  positive  probent : 
Mixta,  quae  ita  rem  probant  in  casibus  nonnullis,  ut  in  cieteris 
probent  contrarium  rei. 

Suppose  now  we  have  three  arguments  of  the  pure  kind  lead- 
ing to  the  same  conclusion;  let  their  respective  probabilities  be 


JAMES   BERNOULLI.  71 

c  f  % 

1  —  ,  1  —  ^,  1  —  •     Then  the  resulting  probability  of  the  con- 

elusion  is  1  — ~- .    This  is  obvious  from  the  consideration  that 
adg 

any  one  of  the  arguments  would  establish  the  conclusion,  so  that 

the  conclusion  fails  only  when  all  the  arguments  fail. 

Supj)ose  now  that  we  have  in  addition  two  arguments  of  the 

mixed  kind :    let  their   respective  probabilities  be   — ^^ , . 

Then  James  Bernoulli  gives  for  the  resulting  probability 

,  cfiru 

1  —         -^ 


adg  (ru  +  qt)  ' 

But  this  formula  is  inaccurate.  For  the  supposition  q  =  0  amounts 
to  having  one  argument  absolutehj  decisive  against  the  conclusion, 
while  yet  the  formula  leaves  still  a  certain  probability  for  the 
conclusion.  The  error  was  pointed  out  by  Lambert;  see  Pre  vest 
and  Lhuilier,  Memoir es  de  F Acad.... Berliii  iov  1797. 

123.  The  most  remarkable  subject  contained  in  the  fourth 
part  of  the  Ars  Conjectandi  is  the  enunciation  and  investigation 
of  what  we  now  call  Bernoulli  s  Theorem.  It  is  introduced  in 
terms  which  shew  a  high  opinion  of  its  importance  : 

Hoc  igitur  est  illud  Problema,  quod  evulgauduni  hoc  loco  proposui, 
postquam  jam  per  vicenniiini  pressi,  et  cujus  turn  novitas,  turn  summa 
utilitas  cum  pari  conjuucta  difficultate  omnibus  reliquis  hujus  doc- 
triiiae  capitibus  pondus  et  pretium  superaddere  potest.  Ars  Conjectandij 
page  227.     See  also  De  Moivre's  Doctrine  of  Chances ,  page  2d^. 

We  will  now  state  the  purely  algebraical  part  of  the  theorem. 
Suppose  that  (r  +  s)**'  is  exj)anded  by  the  Binomial  Theorem,  the 
letters  all  denoting  integral  numbers  and  t  being  equal  to  r  +  s. 
Let  u  denote  the  sum  of  the  greatest  term  and  the  n  preceding 
terms  and  the  n  following  terms.  Then  by  taking  n  large  enough 
the  ratio  of  u  to  the  sum  of  all  the  remaining  terms  of  the  expan- 
sion may  be  made  as  gi-eat  as  we  please. 

If  we  wish  that  this  ratio  should  not  be  less  than  c  it  will  be 
sufficient  to  take  n  equal  to  the  greater  of  the  two  following  ex- 
pressions, 


72  JAMES   BERNOULLI. 


log c  +  log  {s -  1)      /^  ^      s    \ s__ 

log  (r  +  1)  -  log  r      V        r  +  1/      r  +  1' 


and  logc  +  log(r-l)      A^ 

loor(s+  l)-log5        V 


(S  +  1)  -  log  5        V  5  +  1/         5+1 

James  Bernoulli's  demonstration  of  this  result  is  long  but 
perfectly  satisfactory ;  it  rests  mainly  on  the  fact  that  the  terms 
in  the  Binomial  series  increase  continuously  up  to  the  greatest 
term,  and  then  decrease  continuously.  We  shall  see  as  we  proceed 
with  the  history  of  our  subject  that  James  Bernoulli's  demonstra- 
tion is  now  superseded  by  the  use  of  Stirling's  Theorem. 

124.  Let  us  now  take  the  application  of  the  algebraical  result 
to  the  Theory  of  Probability.  The  greatest  term  of  (r  +  5)"',  where 
t=r-\-s  is  the  term  involving  r"''^"'.  Let  r  and  s  be  proportional  to 
the  probability  of  the  happening  and  failing  of  an  event  in  a  single 
trial.  Then  the  sum  of  the  2?i  +  1  terms  of  (r  +  s)"^  which  have  the 
greatest  term  for  their  middle  term  corresponds  to  the  probability 
that  in  nt  trials  the  number  of  times  the  event  happens  will  lie 
between  n{r—l)  and  n  (r+  1),  both  inclusive ;  so  that  the  ratio 
of  the  number  of  times  the  event  happens  to  the  whole  number  of 

7*  +  1  T  ~—  1. 

trials  lies  between  and .     Then,    by  taking  for  n  the 

t  f 

greater  of  the  two  expressions  in  the  preceding  article,  we  have 

the  odds  of  c  to  1,  that  the  ratio  of  the  number  of  times  the  event 

7*  +  1 

happens  to  the  whole   number  of  trials  lies  between  and 

r-1 

t      ' 
As  an  example  James  Bernoulli  takes 

r  =  30,    5=20,    t=50. 

He    finds  for   the    odds   to  be  1000   to   1  that  the  ratio  of  the 
number  of  times  the  event  happens  to  the  whole  number  of  trials 

31         29    .       . 

shall  lie  between  —r  and  ~r,  it  will  be  sufficient  to  make  25550 

t)0         50 

trials ;  for  the  odds  to  be  10000  to  1,  it  will  be  sufficient  to  make 

31258  trials  ;  for  the  odds  to  be  100000  to  1,  it  will  be  sufficient 

to  make  36966  trials;  and  so  on. 


JA3IES   BERNOULLI.  73 

125.  Suppose  then  that  we  have  an  urn  containing  white  balls 

and  black  balls,  and  that  the  ratio  of  the  number  of  the  former 

to  the  latter  is  known  to  he  that  of  3  to  2.     We  learn  from  the 

preceding  result  that  if  we  make  25550  drawings  of  a  single  ball, 

replacing  each  ball  after  it  is  drawn,  the  odds  are  1000  to  1  that 

31  29 

the  white  balls  drawn  lie  between  —-  and  — :  of  the  whole  num- 

50  oO 

ber  drawn.     This  is  the  direct  use  of  James  Bernoulli's  theorem. 

But  he   himself  proposed  to  employ  it  inversely  in  a  far  more 

important   way.     Suppose  that  in  the  preceding  illustration  we 

do  not  know  anything  beforehand  of  the  ratio  of  the  white  balls 

to  the  black  ;  but  that  we  have  made  a  larg-e  number  of  drawings, 

and  have  obtained  a  white  ball  B  times,  and  a  black  ball  S  times : 

then    according    to  James  Bernoulli    we   are  to    infer  that  the 

ratio  of  the  white  balls  to  the  black  balls  in  the  urn  is  approxi- 

r) 

mately  — .     To  determine  the  precise  numerical  estimate  of  the 

probability  of  this  inference  requires  further  investigation :  we 
shall  find  as  we  proceed  that  this  has  been  done  in  two  ways, 
by  an  inversion  of  James  Bernoulli's  theorem,  or  by  the  aid  of 
another  theorem  called  Bayes's  theorem  ;  the  results  apj^roximately 
agree.     See  Laplace,  Theorie.,.des  Proh....  pages  282  and  3CG. 

126.  We  have  spoken  of  the  inverse  use  of  James  Bernoulli's 
theorem  as  the  most  important;  and  it  is  clear  that  he  himself 
was  fully  aware  of  this.  This  use  of  the  theorem  was  that  which 
Leibnitz  found  it  difficult  to  admit,  and  which  James  Bernoulli 
maintained  against  him;  seethe  correspondence  quoted  in  Art.  59, 
pages  77,  83,  87,  94,  97. 

127.  A  memoir  on  infinite  series  follows  the  Ars  Conjectandi, 
and  occupies  pages  24)1 — 306  of  the  volume ;  this  is  contained  in 
the  collected  edition  of  James  Bernoulli's  works,  Geneva,  1744  :  it 
is  there  broken  up  into  parts  and  distributed  through  the  two 
volumes  of  which  the  edition  consists. 

This  memoir  is  unconnected  with  our  subject,  and  we  will 
therefore  only  briefly  notice  some  points  of  interest  which  it 
presents. 


74  JAJVIES  BERNOULLI. 

128,  James  Bernoulli  enforces  tlie  importance  of  the  subject 
in  the  following  terms,  page  243, 

Cseterum  quantse  sit  necessitatis  pariter  et  utilitatis  hasc  serierum 
contemplatio,  ei  sane  ignotum  esse  non  poterit,  qui  perspectum  habuerit, 
ejusmodi  series  sacram  quasi  esse  anchoram,  ad  quam  in  maxime  arduis 
et  desperatse  solutionis  Problematibus,  ubi  omnes  alias  humani  ingenii 
vires  naufragium  passae,  velut  ultimi  remedii  loco  confugiendum  est. 

129.  The  principal  artifice  employed  by  James  Bernoulli  in 
this  memoir  is  that  of  subtracting  one  series  from  another,  thus 
obtaining  a  third  series.     For  example, 

let  /S'=l  +  R+iT+  ...  + 


2  '  3 n  +  l  ' 

a  ..11  11 

then  b=        l  +  -^  +  o+"-  +  ~-^ TT  5 

z      3  n     71  +  1 

1  r  ^  -,  111  11 

therefore  0  =  —  1  +  ^ — ^  +  ^ — ^  +  - — -  +  . . .  +  -7 — — rr  + 


1  .  2  '  2  .  3  '  3  .  4   '  •"   '  7i(?i  +  l)      n  +  1  ' 

,       .  Ill  1,1 

therelore  -z — ^  +  - — ^  +  ^ — r  +  •  • .  H — 7 — — ty  =  1  — 


1.2'   2. 33. 4'         '  n{n+l)  n+1' 

Thus  the  sum  of  n  terms  of  the  series,  of  which  the  r^^  term  is 
1  .         n 

IS 


r  (r  +  1)  '         n  +  1  ' 

ISO.     James  Bernoulli   says  that  his  brother  first  observed 

1111 

that  the  sum  of  the  infinite  series  -+  —  +-  +  y  +  ...is  infinite ; 

i.  jLi  O  ^ 

and  he  gives  his  brother's  demonstration  and  his  own  ;  see  his 
page  250. 

131.    James  Bernoulli  shews  that  the  sum  of  the  infinite  series 
_  _|_  —  ^       +      -j-  . . .  is  finite,  but  confesses  himself  unable  to  give 

the  sum.     He  says,  page  254,     Si  quis  inveniat  nobisque  commu- 
nicet,  quod  industriam  nostram  elusit  hactenus,  magnas  de  nobis 

crratias  feret.     The  sum  is  now  known  to  be  7r  ;  this  result  is  due 

to  Euler :  it  is  given  in  his  Introductio  in  Analysin  Infinitorum, 
1748,  Vol.  L  page  130. 


JAMES  BERNOULLI.  75 

132.  James  Bernoulli  seems  to  be  on  more  familiar  terms 
with  infinity  than  mathematicians  of  the  present  day.  On  his 
page  262  we  find  him  stating,  correctly,  that  the  sum  of  the  infinite 

series  —-r  +  —p^+  -77,  +  -77  +  . . .  is  infinite,  for  the  series  is  greater 
\/i       v^       V^       V"* 

1111 

than  7  +  Q  +  Q  +  7  +  ...     He  adds  that  the  sum  of  all  the  odd 

terms  of  the  first  series  is  to  the  sum  of  all  the  even  terms  as 
\/2  —  1  is  to  1 ;  so  that  the  sum  of  the  odd  terms  would  appear  to 
be  less  than  the  sum  of  the  even  terms,  which  is  impossible.  But 
the  paradox  does  not  disturb  James  Bernoulli,  for  he  adds, 

...cujus  evavTLO(fiaveLas  rationem,  etsi  ex  infiniti  natiira  finito  intel- 
lectui  comprehendi  non  posse  videatur,  nos  tamen  satis  perspectam 
habemus. 

183.  At  the  end  of  the  volume  containing  the  Ars  Conjectandi 
we  have  the  Lettre  a  un  Amy,  sur  les  Parties  da  Jen  de  Faume, 
to  which  we  have  alluded  in  Art.  97. 

The  nature  of  the  problem  discussed  may  be  thus  stated. 
Suppose  A  and  B  two  players ;  let  them  play  a  set  of  games,  say 
five,  that  is  to  say,  the  player  gains  the  set  who  first  wins  five 
games.  Then  a  certain  number  of  sets,  say  four,  make  a  match. 
It  is  required  to  estimate  the  chances  of  A  and  B  in  various  states 
of  the  contest.  Suppose  for  example  that  A  has  won  two  sets, 
and  B  has  won  one  set ;  and  that  in  the  set  now  current  A  has 
won  two  games  and  B  has  won  one  game.  The  problem  is  thus 
somewhat  similar  in  character  to  the  Problem  of  Points,  but  more 
complicated.  James  Bernoulli  discusses  it  very  fully,  and  presents 
his  result  in  the  form  of  tables.  He  considers  the  case  in  which  the 
players  are  of  unequal  skill ;  and  he  solves  various  problems  arising 
from  particular  circumstances  connected  with  the  game  of  tennis 
to  which  the  letter  is  specially  devoted. 

On  the  second  page  of  the  letter  is  a  very  distinct  statement 
of  the  use  of  the  celebrated  theorem  known  by  the  name  of  Ber- 
noulli ;  see  Art.  123. 

134.  One  problem  occurs  in  ihi^  Lettre  a  un  Amy...  which 
it  may  be  interesting  to  notice. 

Suppose  that  A  and  B  engage  in  play,  and  that  each  in  turn 


76  JAMES   BERNOULLI. 

by  the  laws  of  tlie  game  has  an  advantage  over  his  antagonist.  Thus 
suppose  that  ^'s  chance  of  winning  in  the  1st,  3rd,  5th...  games  is 
always  p,  and  his  chance  of  losing  q)  and  in  the  2nd,  4th,  6th... 
games  suppose  that  ^'s  chance  of  winning  is  q  and  his  chance  of 
losing/?.  The  chance  of  B  is  found  by  taking  that  of  A  from 
unity ;  so  that  B's  chance  is  p  or  5'  according  as  ^'s  is  q  or  p. 

Now  let  A  and  B  play,  and  suppose  that  the  stake  is  to  be 
assigned  to  the  player  who  first  wins  n  games.  There  is  however  to 
be  this  peculiarity  in  their  contest :  If  each  of  them  obtains  n  —  1 
games  it  will  be  necessary  for  one  of  them  to  win  two  games  in 
succession  to  decide  the  contest  in  his  favour;  if  each  of  them 
wins  one  of  the  next  two  games,  so  that  each  has  scored  n  games, 
the  same  law  is  to  hold,  namely,  that  one  must  win  two  games  in 
succession  to  decide  the  contest  in  his  favour ;  and  so  on. 

Let  us  now  suppose  that  n  =  2,  and  estimate  the  advantage  of 
A.     Let  X  denote  this  advantage,  >S^  the  whole  sum  to  be  gained. 

Now  A  may  win  the  first  and  second  games  ;  his  chance  for 
this  \^  pq,  and  then  he  receives  S.  He  may  win  the  first  game, 
and  lose  the  second  ;  his  chance  for  this  is  p^.  He  may  lose  the 
first  game  and  win  the  second;  his  chance  for  this  is  ^.  In  the 
last  two  cases  his  position  is  neither  better  nor  worse  than  at  first ; 
that  is  he  may  be  said  to  receive  x. 

Thus  X  =  pq  S -{■  {p"^ -{- q^)  X  \ 

r  pq  S  pq  S      S 

therefore  a?=.,    ^   ., 2=  ^  =7T  • 

1  —p  —  q       zpq      A 

Hence  of  course  J5's  advantage  is  also  -  .     Thus  the  players 

are  on  an  equal  footing. 

James  Bernoulli  in  his  way  obtains  this  result.  He  says  that 
whatever  may  be  the  value  of  n,  the  players  are  on  an  equal  foot- 
ing ;  he  verifies  the  statement  by  calculating  numerically  the 
chances  for  n  =  2,  8,  4  or  5,  taking^  =  2q.     See  his  pages  18,  19. 

Perhaps  the  following  remarks  may  be  sufficient  to  shew  that 
whatever  n  may  be,  the  players  must  be  on  an  equal  footing.  By 
the  peculiar  law  of  the  game  which  we  have  explained,  it  follows 
that  the  contest  is  not  decided  until  one  player  has  gained  at  least 
n  games,  and  is  at  least  two  games  in  advance  of  his  adversary. 


JAMES   BERNOULLI.  77 

Thus  the  contest  is  either  decided  in  an  even  number  of  games, 
or  else  in  an  odd  number  of  games  in  which  the  victor  is  at  least 
three  games  in  advance  of  his  adversary :  in  the  last  case  no  ad- 
vantage or  disadvantage  will  accrue  to  either  player  if  they  play 
one  more  game  and  count  it  in.  Thus  the  contest  may  be  con- 
ducted without  any  change  of  probabilities  under  the  following 
laws:  the  number  of  games  shall  be  even,  and  the  victor  gain  not 
less  than  n  and  be  at  least  two  in  advance  of  his  adversary.  But 
since  the  number  of  games  is  to  be  even  we  see  that  the  two 
players  are  on  an  equal  footing. 

135.     Gouraud  has  given  the  following  summary  of  the  merits 
of  the  A7^s  Conjectandi ;  see  his  page  28  : 

Tel  est  ce  livre  de  YArs  conjectandi,  livre  qui,  si  Ton  considere  le 
temps  ou  il  fut  compose,  I'origiualite,  Fetendue  et  la  penetration 
d'esprit  qu'y  montra  son  autenr,  la  fecondite  etonnante  de  la  constitution 
scientifique  qu'il  donna  au  Calcul  des  probabilites,  I'influence  enfin  qu'il 
devait  exercer  sur  deux  siecles  d'analyse,  pourra  sans  exageration  etre 
regarde  comme  un  des  monuments  les  plus  importants  de  I'histoire  des 
matliematiques.  II  a  place  a  jamais  le  nom  de  Jacques  Bernoulli  parmi 
les  noms  de  ces  inventeurs,  a  qui  la  posterite  reconnaissante  rejiorte  tou- 
jours  et  a  bon  droit,  le  plus  pur  merite  des  decouvertes,  que  sans  leur 
premier  effort,  elle  n'aurait  jamais  su  faire. 

Tliis  2^aneg}Tic,  however,  seems  to  neglect  the  simple  fact  r.f 
the  date  of  inihlication  of  the  Ars  Conjectandi,  which  was  really 
subsequent  to  the  first  appearance  of  Montmort  and  De  Moivre  in 
this  field  of  mathematical  investigation.  The  researches  of  James 
Bernoulli  were  doubtless  the  earlier  in  existence,  but  they  were 
the  later  in  appearance  before  the  world ;  and  thus  the  influence 
which  they  might  have  exercised  had  been  already  produced.  The 
problems  in  the  first  three  parts  of  the  Ars  Conjectandi  cannot  be 
considered  equal  in  importance  or  difliculty  to  those  which  we 
find  investigated  by  Montmort  and  De  Moivre ;  but  the  memorable 
theorem  in  the  fourth  part,  which  justly  bears  its  author's  name, 
will  ensure  him  a  permanent  \)\'d.cQ  in  the  history  of  the  Theory  of 
Probability. 


CHAPTER    VIII. 


MONTMORT. 

186.  The  work  which  next  claims  attention  is  that  of  Mont- 
mort;  it  is  entitled  Essai  d! Analyse  stir  les  Jeux  de  Hazards. 

Fontenelle's  Hloge  de  M.  de  Montmort  is  contained  in  the 
volume  for  1719  of  the  Hist,  de  V Acad... Paris,  which  was  pub- 
lished in  1721 ;  from  this  we  take  a  few  particulars. 

Pierre  Eemond  de  Montmort  was  born  in  1678.  Under  the 
influence  of  his  guide,  master,  and  friend,  Malebranche,  he  devoted 
himself  to  religion,  philosophy,  and  mathematics.  He  accepted 
with  reluctance  a  canonry  of  Notre-Dame  at  Paris,  which  he  re- 
linquished in  order  to  marry.  He  continued  his  simple  and 
retired  life,  and  we  are  told  that,  j^ar  un  honheur  assez  singidier 
le  mariage  lui  rendit  sa  maison  plus  agreahle.  In  1708  he  pub- 
lished his  work  on  Chances,  where  with  the  courage  of  Columbus 
he  revealed  a  new  world  to  mathematicians. 

After  Montmort's  work  appeared  De  Moivre  published  his  essay 
De  Mensura  Sortis.     Fontenelle  says, 

Je  ne  dissimulerai  point  qui  M.  de  Montmort  fut  vivement  pique 
de  cet  ouvrage,  qui  lui  parut  avoir  ete  entierement  fait  sur  le  sien,  et 
d'apres  le  sien.  II  est  vrai,  qu'il  y  6toit  loue,  et  n'etoit-ce  pas  assez, 
dira-t-on  1  mais  un  Seigneur  de  fief  n'en  quittera  pas  pour  des  louanges 
celui  qu'il  pretend  lui  devoir  foi  et  liommage  des  terres  qu'il  tient  de 
lui.  Je  parle  selon  sa  pretention,  et  ne  decide  nulloinent  s'il  etoit  en 
efi'et  le  Seigneur. 

Montmort  died  of  small  pox  at  Paris  in  1719.  He  had  been 
engaged  on  a  work  entitled  Histoire  de  la  Geometrie,  but  -had  not 


MONTMORT.  79 

proceeded  far  with  it;  on  this  subject  Fontenelle  has  some  inter- 
esting remarks.  See  also  Montucla's  Histoire  des  Mathematiques, 
first  edition,  Preface,  page  vii. 

137.  There  are  two  editions  of  Montmort's  work;  the  first 
appeared  in  1708;  the  second  is  sometimes  said  to  have  appeared 
in  1713,  but  the  date  1714  is  on  the  title  page  of  my  copy,  which 
appears  to  have  been  a  present  to  'sGravesande  from  the  author. 
Both  editions  are  in  quarto;  the  first  contains  189  pages  with 
a  preface  of  xxiv  pages,  and  the  second  contains  414  pages  with 
a  preface  and  advertisement  of  XLII  pages.  The  increased  bulk 
of  the  second  edition  arises,  partly  from  the  introduction  of  a 
treatise  on  combinations  which  occupies  pages  1 — 72,  and  partly 
from  the  addition  of  a  series  of  letters  which  passed  between 
Montmort  and  Nicholas  Bernoulli  with  one  letter  from  John 
Bernoulli.  The  name  of  Montmort  does  not  appear  on  the  title 
page  or  in  the  work,  except  once  on  page  338,  where  it  is  used 
with  respect  to  a  place. 

Any  reference  which  we  make  to  Montmort's  work  must  be 
taken  to  apply  to  the  second  edition  unless  the  contrary  is  stated. 

Montucla  says,  page  394,  speaking  of  the  second  edition  of 
Montmort's  work,  Cette  edition,  independamment  de  ses  aug- 
mentations et  corrections  faites  a  la  premiere,  est  remarquable  par 
de  belles  gravures  a  la  tete  de  chaque  partie.  These  engravings 
are  four  in  number,  and  they  occur  also  in  the  first  edition,  and  of 
course  the  impressions  will  naturally  be  finer  in  the  earlier  edition. 
It  is  desirable  to  correct  the  eiTor  implied  in  Montucla's  state- 
ment, because  the  work  is  scarce,  and  thus  those  who  merely  wish 
for  the  engravings  may  direct  their  attention  to  the  first  edition, 
leaving  the  second  for  mathematicians, 

138.  Leibnitz  corresponded  with  Montmort  and  his  brother; 
and  he  records  a  very  favourable  opinion  of  the  work  we  are  now 
about  to  examine.  He  says,  however,  J'aurois  souhaite  les  loix 
des  Jeux  un  peu  mieux  decrites,  et  les  termes  expliques  en  favour 
des  dtrangers  et  de  la  posterite.  Leibnitii  Opera  Omnia,  ed. 
Dutens,  Vol.  v.  pages  17  and  28. 

Reference  is  also  made  to  Montmort  and  his  book  in  the  cor- 
respondence between  Leibnitz  and  John  and  Nicholas  Bernoulli ; 


80  MONTMORT. 

see  the  work  cited  in  Art.  59,  pages  827,  836,  837,  8-i2,  846,  903, 
985,  987,  989. 

139.  We  will  now  give  a  detailed  account  of  Montmort's 
work ;  we  will  take  the  second  edition  as  our  standard,  and  point 
out  as  occasion  may  require  when  our  remarks  do  not  apply  to 
the  first  edition  also. 

140.  The  preface  occupies  XXIV  pages.  Montmort  refers  to 
the  fact  that  James  Bernoulli  had  been  engaged  on  a  work  entitled 
De  arte  conjectandi,  which  his  premature  death  had  prevented  him 
from  completing.  Montmort's  introduction  to  these  studies  had 
arisen  from  the  request  of  some  friends  that  he  would  determine 
the  advantage  of  the  banker  at  the  game  of  Pharaon;  and  he  had 
been  led  on  to  compose  a  work  which  might  compensate  for  the 
loss  of  Bernoulli's. 

Montmort  makes  some  judicious  observations  on  the  foolish 
and  superstitious  notions  which  were  prevalent  among  persons 
devoted  to  games  of  chance,  and  proposes  to  check  these  by  shew- 
ing, not  only  to  such  persons  but  to  men  in  general,  that  there 
are  rules  in  chance,  and  that  for  want  of  knowing  these  rules 
mistakes  are  made  which  entail  adverse  results;  and  these  results 
men  impute  to  destiny  instead  of  to  their  own  ignorance.  Per- 
haps however  he  speaks  rather  as  a  philosopher  than  as  a  gambler 
when  he  says  positively  on  his  page  vili, 

On  joueroit  sans  donte  avec  plus  d'agrement  si  Ton  pouvoit  sgavoir 
a  chaqne  coup  I'esperance  qu'on  a  de  gagner,  ou  le  risque  que  I'on  court 
de  perdre.  On  seroit  plus  tranquile  sur  les  evenemens  du  jeu,  et  on 
sentiroit  mieux  le  ridicule  de  ces  plaintes  continuelles  ausquelles  se 
laissent  aller  la  plupart  des  Joueurs  dans  les  rencontres  les  plus  com- 
munes, lorsqu'elles  leur  sout  conti'aires. 

141.  Montmort  divides  his  work  into  four  parts.  The  first 
part  contains  the  theory  of  combinations ;  the  second  part  discusses 
certain  games  of  chance  depending  on  cards ;  the  third  part  dis- 
cusses certain  games  of  chance  depending  on  dice;  the  fourth 
part  contains  the  solution  of  various  problems  in  chances,  including 
the  five  problems  proposed  by  Huygens.  To  these  four  parts 
must  be  added  the  letters  to  which  we  have  alluded  in  Art.  137. 


MONTMORT.  81 

Montmort  gives  his  reasons  for  not  devoting  a  part  to  the  appli- 
cation of  his  subject  to  political,  economical,  and  moral  questions, 
in  conformity  with  the  known  design  of  James  Bernoulli;  see  his 
pages  XIII — XX.  His  reasons  contain  a  good  appreciation  of  the 
difficulty  that  must  attend  all  such  applications,  and  he  thus  states 
the  conditions  under  which  we  may  attempt  them  with  advantage: 
1^.  borner  la  question  que  Ton  se  propose  h  un  petit  nombre  de 
suppositions,  etablies  sur  des  faits  certains;  2".  faire  abstraction  do 
toutes  les  circonstances  ausquelles  la  liberte  de  I'homme,  cet 
ocueil  perpetuel  de  nos  connoissances,  pourroit  avoir  quelque  part. 
Montmort  praises  highly  the  memoir  by  Halley,  which  we  have 
already  noticed ;  and  also  commends  Petty's  Political  A  rithmetic ; 
see  Arts.  57,  01. 

Montmort  refers  briefly  to  his  predecessors,  Huygens,  Pascal, 
and  Format.  He  says  that  his  work  is  intended  principally  for 
mathematicians,  and  that  he  has  fully  explained  the  various  games 
which  he  discusses  because,  pour  I'ordinaire  les  S^avans  ne  sont 
pas  Joueurs;  see  his  page  xxiii. 

142.  After  the  preface  follows  an  Avertissement  which  was  not 
in  the  first  edition.  Montmort  sa3^s  that  two  small  treatises  on 
the  subject  had  appeared  since  his  first  edition;  namely  a  thesis 
by  Nicolas  Bernoulli  De  arte  conjectandi  in  Jure,  and  a  memoir 
by  De  Moivre,  De  meiisura  sortis. 

Montmort  seems  to  have  been  much  displeased  with  the  terms 
in  which  reference  was  made  to  him  by  De  Moivre.  De  Moivre 
had  said, 

Ilugenius,  primus  quod  sciani  regulas  tradidit  ad  istius  generis  Pro- 
blematum  Solutionem,  quas  nuperrimus  autor  Gallus  variis  exemplis 
pulclire  illustravit ;  sed  non  videntur  viri  clarissimi  ea  simplicitate  ac 
generalitate  usi  fuisse  quam  natura  rei  postulabat :  etenirn  dum  p]  ures 
quantitates  incognitas  usurpant,  ut  varias  Collusorum  conditiones  re- 
praesentent,  calculum  siumi  nimis  perplexum  redduut ;  diimque  Colhi- 
sorum  dexteritatem  semper  aequalem  pomint,  doctriuam  hanc  ludorum 
intra  limites  nimis  arctos  continent. 

Montmort  seems  to  have  taken  needless  offence  at  these  words ; 
he  thought  his  own  performances  were  undervalued,  and  accord- 
ingly he  defends  his  own  claims :  this  leads  him  to  give  a  sketch 

6 


82  MOXTMORT. 

of  the  history  of  the  Theory  of  Probability  from  its  origin.  He 
attributes  to  himself  the  merit  of  having  explored  a  subject  which 
had  been  only  slightly  noticed  and  then  entirely  forgotten  for 
sixty  years ;  see  his  page  xxx. 

143.  The  first  part  of  Montmort's  work  is  entitled  TraiU  des 
Combinaisons ;  it  occupies  pages  1 — 72.  Montmort  says,  on  his 
page  XXV,  that  he  has  here  collected  the  theorems  on  Combina- 
tions which  were  scattered  over  the  work  in  the  first  edition,  and 
that  he  has  added  some  theorems. 

Montmort  begins  by  explaining  the  properties  of  Pascal's  Arith- 
metical Triangle.  He  gives  the  general  expression  for  the  term 
which  occupies  an  assigned  place  in  the  Arithmetical  Tiiangle.  He 
shews  how  to  find  the  sum  of  the  squares,  cubes,  fourth  powers, . . . 
of  the  first  n  natural  numbers.  He  refers,  on  his  page  20,  to  a 
book  called  the  New  introduction  to  the  Mathematics  written  by 
M.  Johnes,  scavant  Geometre  Anglois.  The  author  here  meant  is 
one  who  is  usually  described  as  the  father  of  Sir  William  Jones. 
Montmort  then  investigates  the  number  of  permutations  of  an 
assigned  set  of  things  taken  in  an  assigned  number  together. 

14-i.  Much  of  this  part  of  Montmort's  work  would  however 
be  now  considered  to  belong  rather  to  the  chapter  on  Chances 
than  to  the  chapter  on  Combinations  in  a  treatise  on  Algebra. 
We  have  in  fact  numerous  examples  about  drawing  cards  and 
throwing  dice. 

We  will  notice  some  of  the  more  interesting  points  in  this 
part.  We  may  remark  that  in  order  to  denote  the  number  of 
combinations  of  n  things  taken  r  at  a  time,  Montmort  uses  the 
symbol  of  a  small  rectangle  with  n  above  it  and  r  below  it. 

145.  Montmort  proposes  to  establish  the  Binomial  Theorem; 
see  his  page  32.  He  says  that  this  theorem  may  be  demonstrated 
in  various  ways.  His  own  method  will  be  seen  from  an  example. 
Suppose  we  require  (a  +  6)^  Conceive  that  we  have  four  counters 
each  having  two  faces,  one  black  and  one  white.  Then  Montmort 
has  already  shewn  by  the  aid  of  the  Arithmetical  Triangle  that 
if  the  four  counters  are  thrown  promiscuously  there  is  one  way 
ia  which  all  the  faces  presented  will  be  black,  four  ways  in  which 


MONTMORT.  83 

three  faces  will  be  black  and  one  white,  six  ways  in  which  two 
faces  will  be  black  and  two  white;  and  so  on.  Then  he  reasons 
thus:  we  know  by  the  rules  for  multiplication  that  in  order  to 
raise  a  +  h  to  the  fourth  power  (1)  we  must  take  the  fourth  power 
of  a  and  the  fourth  power  of  h,  which  is  the  same  thing  as  taking 
the  four  black  faces  and  the  four  white  faces,  (2)  we  must  take 
the  cube  of  a  with  b,  and  the  cube  of  b  with  a  in  as  many  ways  as 
possible,  which  is  the  same  thing  as  taking  the  three  black  faces 
with  one  white  face,  and  the  three  white  faces  with  one  black 
face,  (3)  we  must  take  the  square  of  a  with  the  square  of  b  in 
as  many  ways  as  possible,  which  is  the  same  thing  as  taking  the 
two  black  faces  with  the  two  white  faces.  Hence  the  coefficients 
in  the  Binomial  Theorem  must  be  the  numbers  1,  4,  6,  which  we 
have  already  obtained  in  considering  the  cases  which  can  arise 
with  the  four  counters. 

l-iG.  Thus  in  fact  Montmort  argues  a  priori  that  the  coeffi- 
cients in  the  expansion  of  {a  +  hy  must  be  equal  to  the  numbers  of 
cases  corresponding  to  the  different  ways  in  which  the  white  and 
black  faces  may  appear  if  n  counters  are  thrown  2)romiscuously, 
each  counter  having  one  black  face  and  one  white  face. 

Montmort  gives  on  his  page  3i  a  similar  interpretation  to 
the  coefficients  of  the  multinomial  theorem.  Hence  we  see  that 
he  in  some  cases  passed  from  theorems  in  Chances  to  theorems  in 
pure  Algebra,  while  we  now  pass  more  readily  from  theorems  in 
pure  Algebra  to  their  application  to  the  doctrine  of  Chances. 

147.  On  his  page  42  Montmort  has  the  following  problem: 
There  are  jj  dice  each  having  the  same  number  of  faces;  find  the 
number  of  ways  in  which  when  they  are  thrown  at  random  we  can 
have  a  aces,  b  twos,  c  threes,  . . . 

The  result  will  be  in  modern  notation 


\a  \b[G... 


He  then  proceeds  to  a  case  a  little  more  complex,  namely 
where  we  are  to  have  a  of  one  sort  of  faces,  h  of  another  sort,  c 
of  a  third  sort,  and  so  on,  without  specifying  whether  the  a  faces 

G— 2 


8^  MONTMOET. 

are  to  be  aces,  or  twos,  or  threes,  ,..,  and  similarly  without  specify- 
ing for  the  h  faces,  or  the  c  faces, . . . 

He  had  given  the  result  for  this  problem  in  his  first  edition, 
page  137,  where  the  factors  B,  C,  JD,  E,  F,...  must  however  be 
omitted  from  his  denominator ;  he  suppressed  the  demonstration 
in  his  first  edition  because  he  said  it  would  be  long  and  abstruse, 
and  only  intelligible  to  such  persons  as  were  capable  of  discovering 
it  for  themselves. 

148.  On  his  page  46  Montmort  gives  the  following  problem, 
which  is  new  in  the  second  edition  :  There  are  n  dice  each  having 
/faces,  marked  with  the  numbers  from  1  to/;  they  are  thrown  at 
random :  determine  the  number  of  ways  in  which  the  sum  of  the 
numbers  exhibited  by  the  dice  will  be  equal  to  a  given  number  p. 

"We  should  now  solve  the  problem  by  finding  the  coefficient 
of  x^  in  the  expansion  of 

(a; +  03^  +  03'+  ...+x^Y, 

/I — x^y^ 

that  is  the  coefficient  of  x^'"'  in  the  expansion  of  I  = J  ,  that  is 

in  the  expansion  of  (1  —  x)'""  (1  —  x^y.     Let  p  —  n  =  s;  then  the 
required  number  is 

n  (ii+l)  ...  (n-h  s  —1)  71  (72  +  1)  ...  (n+s  —f—  1) 


«-/ 


n(n-l)  n(n  +  V)  ...  (n+ s  —2f- 1) 
1.2  l.s-2/ 


The  series  is  to  be  continued  so  long  as  all  the  factors  which 
occur  are  positive.  Montmort  demonstrates  the  formula,  but  in  a 
much  more  laborious  way  than  the  above. 

149.  The  preceding  formula  is  one  of  the  standard  results  of 
the  subject,  and  we  must  now  trace  its  history.  The  formula  was 
first  published  by  De  Moivre  without  demonstration  in  the  Be 
Mensura  Sortis.  Montmort  says,  on  his  page  364,  that  it  was  derived 
from  page  141  of  his  first  edition;  but  this  assertion  is  quite  un- 
founded, for  all  that  we  have  in  Montmort's  first  edition,  at  the 
place  cited,  is  a  table  of  the  various  throws  which  can  be  made 
with  any  number  of  dice  up  to  nine  in  number.     Montmort  how- 


MONTMORT.  85 

ever  shews  by  tlie  evidence  of  a  letter  addressed  to  John  Bernoulli, 
dated  15th  November,  1710,  that  he  was  himself  acquainted  with 
the  formula  before  it  was  published  by  De  Moivi-e ;  see  Montmort, 
page  307.  De  Moivre  first  published  his  demonstration  in  his 
Miscellanea  Analytica,  1730,  where  he  ably  replied  to  the  asser- 
tion that  the  formula  had  been  derived  from  the  first  edition  of 
Montmort's  work  ;  see  Miscellama  Analytica,  pages  191 — 197. 
De  Moivre's  demonstration  is  the  same  as  that  which  we  have 
given. 

150.  Montmort  then  proceeds  to  a  more  difficult  question. 
Suppose  we  have  three  sets  of  cards,  each  set  containing  ten  cards 
marked  with  the  numbers  1,  2,  . . .  10.  If  three  cards  are  taken 
out  of  the  thirty,  it  is  required  to  find  in  how  many  ways  the 
sum  of  the  numbers  on  the  cards  will  amount  to  an  assigned 
number. 

In  this  problem  the  assigned  number  may  arise  (1)  from  three 
cards  no  two  of  which  are  of  the  same  set,  (2)  from  three  cards 
two  of  which  are  of  one  set  and  the  third  of  another  set,  (3)  from 
three  cards  all  of  the  same  set.  The  first  case  is  treated  in  the 
problem,  Article  148;  the  other  two  cases  are  new. 

Montmort  here  gives  no  general  solution;  he  only  shews  how  a 
table  may  be  made  registering  all  the  required  results. 

He  sums  up  thus,  page  62 :  Cette  methode  est  un  peu  longue, 
mais  j'ai  de  la  peine  a  croire  qu'on  puisse  en  trouver  une  plus 
courte. 

The  problem  discussed  here  by  Montmort  may  be  stated  thus : 
We  require  the  number  of  solutions  of  the  equation  x  -\-  y  +  z  =  p, 
under  the  restriction  that  x,  y,  z  shall  be  positive  integers  lying 
between  1  and  10  inclusive,  and  p  a  positive  integer  wdiich  has  an 
assigned  value  lying  between  3  and  30  inclusive. 

151.  In  his  pages  63 — 72  Montmort  discusses  a  problem  in 
the  summation  of  series.  We  should  now  enunciate  it  as  a  general 
question  of  Finite  Differences :  to  find  the  sum  of  any  assigned 
number  of  terms  of  a  series  in  which  the  Finite  Differences  of  a 
certain  order  are  zero. 

In  modern  notation,  let  iin  denote  the  n^^  term  and  suppose 
that  the  {in  + 1)*^  Finite  Difference  is  zero. 


86  MONTMOET. 

Then  it  is  shewn  in  works  on  Finite  Differences,  that 

i(n  =  %  +  'i^^Uo  4-  -J — 2~    -^'^^^  +  •  •  • 

,  yi(?i--l)  ...(??-m+l)  .,„ 

i -» j 11   Uq  . 

[m 

This  formula  Montmort  gives,  using  A,  B,  C,...  for  Aw^j  AV^, 

By   the   aid   of  this  formula  the  summation  of  an   assigned 

number  of  terms  of  the  proposed  series  is  reduced  to  depend  on  the 

,.          ^        .          ^      ,.,     n  (n—1)  ...  (n  —  r+1)  . 

summation   of   series    of  which    — ^ — j — ^ ^   may  be 

taken  as  the  type  of  the  general  term  ;  and  such  summations  have 
been  already  effected  by  means  of  the  Arithmetical  Triangle  and 
its  properties. 

152.  Montmort  naturally  attaches  great  importance  to  this 
general  investigation,  which  is  new  in  the  second  edition.  He 
says,  page  ^5^ 

Ce  Problerae  a,  comme  Ton  voit,  toute  I'etendue  et  toute  I'universa- 
lite  possible,  et  semble  ne  rien  laisser  a  desirer  sur  cette  matiere,  qui  n'a 
encore  et6  traitee  par  personne,  que  je  s^ache  :  j'en  avois  obmis  la  de- 
monstration dans  le  Journal  des  Sgavans  du  mois  de  Mars  1711. 

De  Moivi'e  in  his  Doctrine  of  Chances  uses  the  rule  which 
Montmort  here  demonstrates.  In  the  first  edition  of  the  Doctrine 
of  Chances,  page  29,  we  are  told  that  the  "Demonstration  may 
be  had  from  the  Methodus  Differentialis  of  Sir  Isaac  Xewton, 
printed  in  his  Analysis!'  In  the  second  edition  of  the  Doctrine 
of  Chances,  page  52,  and  in  the  third  edition,  page  59,  the  origin 
of  the  rule  is  carried  further  back,  namely,  to  the  fifth  Lemma  of 
the  Princijna,  Book  iii.    See  also  Miscellanea  Analytica,  page  152. 

De  Moivre  seems  here  hardly  to  do  full  justice  to  Montmort  ; 
for  the  latter  is  fairly  entitled  to  the  credit  of  the  first  explicit 
enunciation  of  the  rule,  even  though  it  may  be  implicitl}^  contained 
in  Newton's  Princijna  and  Methodus  Differentialis. 

153.  Montmort's  second  part  occupies  pages  73 — 172  ;  it  re- 


MONTMORT.  87 

lates  to  games  of  chance  involving  cards.  The  first  game  is  that 
called  Pharaon. 

This  game  is  described  by  De  Moivre,  and  some  investigations 
given  by  him  relating  to  it.  De  Moivre  restricts  himself  to  the 
case  of  a  common  pack  of  cards  with  four  suits  ;  Montmort  sup- 
poses the  number  of  suits  to  be  any  number  whatever.  On  the 
other  hand  De  Moivre  calculates  the  percentage  of  gain  of  the 
banker,  which  he  justly  considers  the  most  important  and  difficult 
part  of  the  problem  ;  see  DoctHne  of  Chances,  pages  ix,  77,  105, 

Montmort's  second  edition  gives  the  general  results  more 
compactly  than  the  first. 

15i.  We  shall  make  some  remarks  in  connection  with  Mont- 
mort's investigations  on  Pharaon,  for  the  sake  of  the  summation  of 
certain  series  which  present  themselves. 

155.  Suppose  that  there  are  p  cards  in  the  pack,  which  the 
Banker  has,  and  that  his  adversary's  card  occurs  q  times  in  the 
pack.  Let  ii^  denote  the  Banker's  advantage,  A  the  sum  of  money 
which  his  adversary  stakes.     Montmort  shews  that 

,.  _  g  (y  - 1)  \  A.  (p-q){p-q-^) ,, 

;'^-^.0;-l)  2^+        p[p-l)        ^'-^ 

supposing  that  j9  —  2  is  greater  than  q.     That  is  Montmort  should 

3 

have  this;  but  he  puts  {pq  —  q^)  2 A  +  {(f  —  q)-^A,  on  his  page  89, 

1 

by  mistake  for  q^q  —  l)  -  A)  he  gets  right  on  his  page  90.    Mont- 

mort  is  not  quite  full  enough  in  the  details  of  the  treatment  of 
this  equation.  The  following  results  will  however  be  found  on 
examination. 

If  q  is  even  we  can  by  successive  use  of  the  formula  make  ?/^ 
depend  on  u^ ;  and  then  it  follows  from  the  laws  of  the  game  that 

Wj  is  equal  io  A  \i  q  is  equal  to  2,  and  to  ^  ^  if  ^  is  greater 

than  2.  Thus  we  shall  have,  if  q  is  an  even  number  greater 
than  2, 


'88  MONTMORT. 

,  (;>-g)(p-<7-i)-'-i  I 

If  ^  =  2  the  last  term  within  the  brackets  should  be  doubled. 
Again  if  q  is  odd  we  can  by  successive  use  of  the  fundamental 
formula  make  u^  depend  on  w^^^,  and  if  q  is  greater  than  unity  it 

can  be  shewn  that  u.^,  =  ^-^^  -77  .     Thus  we  shall  have,  if  a  is  an 

^^^      q+1   Z 

odd  number  greater  than  unity, 

,,  _  g(^-^)  1   J  f  1  4.  (p-^)(p-g-l) 
^^-^(^-1)2^|'+      (^-2)(p-3) 

(p-g)(j9-g-l)(j9-g-2)(;.-g-3) 

(^_2)(^-3)(;.-4)(2.-5) 

(i>-g)(;>-g-i)...2 

"^ (i5-2)(i>-3) ^ 

If  ^  =  1  we  have  by  a  special  investigation  Up  =  —  . 

If  we  suppose  q  even  and  p  —  q  not  less  than  q  —  1,  or  q  odd 
and  p  —q  not  less  than  q,  some  of  the  terms  within  the  brackets 
may  be  simplified.  Montmort  makes  these  suppositions,  and  con- 
sequently he  finds  that  the  series  within  the  brackets  may  be 
expressed  as  a  fraction,  of  which  the  common  denominator  is 

{p-2)(p-S)...{p-q  +  l); 

the  numerator  consists  of  a  series,  the  first  term  of  which  is  the 
same  as  the  denominator,  and  the  last  term  is 

fe-2)(^-3)...2.1,  or  (^-l)(^-2)...3.2, 

according  as  q  is  even  or  odd. 

The  matter  contained  in  the  present  article  was  not  given 
by  Montmort  in  his  first  edition ;  it  is  due  to  John  Bernoulli : 
see  Montmort's,  page  287. 


MONTMORT.  89 

156.  We  are  thus  naturally  led  to  consider  the  summation  of 
certain  series. 

Let  0  (71,  r)  =  -^ ^ 

so  that  (j)  {n,  r)  is  the  n^^  number  of  the  (r  +  1)"'  order  of  figurate 
numbers. 

Let  8<f)  (n,  r)  stand  for  <j)  {n,  r)  +  <^  (w  —  2,  ?•)  +  </>  (^  —  4,  r)  +  . . . , 
so  that  S(j>  (n,  r)  is  the  sum  of  the  alternate  terms  of  the  series  of 
figurate  numbers  of  the  (r  +  1)**"  order,  beginning  with  the  w"'  and 
going  backwards.  It  is  required  to  find  an  expression  for  /S'</)  {n,  r). 
It  is  known  that 

0  (n,  r)  +  (l)(n-l,r)  +(f)  {n  -  2,  r)  +  </>  (71  -  3,  r)  +...  =  (/>  (ji,  r  +  1) ; 

and  by  taking  the  terms  in  pairs  it  is  easy  to  see  that 

<j)  (n,  7')  —  (j)  (n  —  l,r)  -{-(f)  [n  —  2, 7^)  —(f>{n  —  3,  ?•)  +  ...  =  S(j)  {n,  r  —  1)  ; 

therefore,  by  addition, 

S(l>  {n,  r)  =  -  (/)  {71,  r-\-l)+^S(i>  (w,  r-  1). 

Hence,  continuing  the  process,  we  shall  have 

1  11 

^^  (w,  ?•)  =  2  ^  ^^'  **  +  ^)  +  3  ^  (^^'  ^')  +  ^  <^  {^h  r  -  1)  + ... 

and  we  must  consider  8<\>  (n,  ^—-n,  if  71  be  even,  and  =  -  (n+1), 
if  n  be  odd. 

We  may  also  obtain  another  expression  for  8<^  {n,  r).  For 
change  w  into  n  +  1  in  the  two  fundamental  relations,  and  subtract, 
instead  of  adding  as  before ;  thus 

>^(/)  (71,  r)  =  i  <^  (n  +  1 ,  r  +  1)  -  ^  ^0  ( ; .  +  1 ,  r  -  1 ) . 
Hence,  continuing  the  process,  we  shall  have 
^(/)(7i,r)=-(/>(7i  +  l,  r  +  1)- ^  </,(«  + 2,7')+^  <3«>(n  + 3,  r-1) 

{-  ly  {-  \Y 

- -^  ^(u  +  r,  2)  +  4^  Sct>(n  +  r,  0). 


90  MONTMORT. 

157.  Montmort's  own  solution  of  the  problem  respecting 
Pharaon  depends  on  the  first  mode  of  summation  explained  in  Art. 
156,  which  coincides  with  Montmort's  own  process.  The  fact  that 
in  Montmort's  result  when  q  is  odd,  ^^  —  1  terms  are  to  be  taken, 
and  when  q^  is  even,  q  terms  are  to  be  taken  and  the  last  doubled, 
depends  on  the  different  values  we  have  to  ascribe  to  8^  (n,  0)  ac- 
cording as  n  is  even  or  odd ;  see  Montmort's  page  98. 

Montmort  gives  another  form  to  his  result  on  his  page  99  ; 
this  he  obtained,  after  the  publication  of  his  first  edition,  from 
Nicolas  Bernoulli.  It  appears  however  that  a  wrong  date  is  here 
assigned  to  the  communication  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli ;  see  Mont- 
mort's page  299.  This  form  depends  on  the  second  mode  of  sum- 
mation explained  in  Art.  156.  It  happens  that  in  applying  this 
second  mode  of  summation  to  the  problem  of  Pharaon  ?i  +  r  is 
always  odd ;  so  that  in  Nicolas  Bernoulli's  form  for  the  result 
we  have  only  one  case,  and  not  two  cases  according  as  q  is  even 
or  odd. 

There  is  a  memoir  by  Euler  on  the  game  of  Pharaon  in  the 
Hist  de  VAcad Berlin  ioY  1764,  in  which  he  expresses  the  ad- 
vantage of  the  Banker  in  the  same  manner  as  Nicolas  Bernoulli. 

158.  Montmort  gives  two  tables  of  numerical  results  respect- 
ing Pharaon.  One  of  these  tables  purports  to  be  an  exact  exhibi- 
tion of  the  Banker's  advantage  at  any  stage  of  the  game,  supposing 
it  played  with  an  ordinary  pack  of  52  cards ;  the  other  table  is  an 
approximate  exhibition  of  the  Banker's  advantage.  A  remark  may 
be  made  with  respect  to  the  former  table.  The  table  consists  of 
four  columns ;  the  first  and  third  are  correct.     The  second  column 

w  +  2 

should  be  calculated  from  the  formula  -r — -, -.  ,  by  puttino^  for  n 

2n  (n  —  1)       -^  ^  ^ 

in  succession  50,  48,  46,  ...  4.     But  in  the  two  copies  of  the  second 

edition  of  Montmort's  book  which  I  have  seen  the  column  is  given 

3117  26 

incorrectly ;  it  begins  with    '       ^     instead  of       ^    ,  and  of  the  re- 

maining  entries  some  are  correct,  but  not  in  their  simplest  forms, 

and  others  are  incorrect.     The  fourth  column  should  be  calculated 

2n  —  5 

from  the  formula  ^w tv-/ i^  ?  ^Y  putting  for  n  in  succession 

z{n—l){n  —  3)     , 

50,  48,  46  ...  4  ;  but  there  are  errors  and  unreduced  results  in  it; 


MONTMORT.  91 

it  begins  with  a  fraction  having  twelve  figures  in  its  denominator, 
which  in  its  simplest  form  would  only  have  four  figures. 

In  the  only  copy  of  the  first  edition  which  I  have  seen  these 
columns  are  given  correctly ;  in  both  editions  the  description  given 
in  the  text  corresponds  not  to  the  incorrect  forms  but  to  the  cor- 
rect forms. 

159.  Montmort  next  discusses  the  game  of  Lansquenet;  this 
discussion  occupies  pages  105 — 129.  It  does  not  appear  to  present 
any  point  of  interest,  and  it  would  be  useless  labour  to  verify  the 
complex  arithmetical  calculations  which  it  involves.  A  few  lines 
which  occurred  on  pages  40  and  41  of  Montmort's  first  edition  are 
omitted  in  the  second  ;  while  the  Articles  84  and  95  of  the  second 
edition  are  new.  Ai'ticle  84  seems  to  have  been  suggested  to 
Montmort  by  John  Bernoulli ;  see  Montmort's  page  288  :  it  relates 
to  a  point  which  James  Bernoulli  had  found  difficult,  as  we  have 
already  stated  in  Art.  119. 

160.  Montmort  next  discusses  the  game  of  Treize ;  this  dis- 
cussion occupies  pages  130 — 143.  The  problem  involved  is  one  of 
considerable  interest,  which  has  maintained  a  permanent  place  in 
works  on  the  Theory  of  Probability. 

The  following  is  the  problem  considered  by  Montmort. 

Suppose  that  we  have  thirteen  cards  numbered  1,  2,  3  ...  up  to 
13 ;  and  that  these  cards  are  thrown  promiscuousl}^  into  a  bag. 
The  cards  are  then  drawn  out  singly ;  required  the  chance  that, 
once  at  least,  the  number  on  a  card  shall  coincide  with  the  number 
expressing  the  order  in  which  it  is  drawn. 

161.  In  his  first  edition  Montmort  did  not  give  any  demon- 
strations of  his  results ;  but  in  his  second  edition  he  gives  two 
demonstrations  which  he  had  received  from  Nicolas  Bernoulli ; 
see  his  pages  301,  302.  We  will  take  the  first  of  these  demon- 
strations. 

Let  a,  h,  c,  d,e, ...  denote  the  cards,  n  in  number.  Then  the  num- 
ber of  possible  cases  is  [n.  The  number  of  cases  in  which  a  is  first 
is  I  yi  —  1.    The  number  of  cases  in  which  h  is  second,  but  a  not  first, 

n  —  1  —  1 7i  —  2.    The  number  of  cases  in  which  c  is  third,  but  a 


IS 


not   first   nor   b   second,    is    |  w  —  1  —  |  ^^  —  2  —  ||?i  —  2  —  |  n  —  31 


92  MONTMORT. 

that    is    \n-l  -2\n-2+\n-S.      The   number    of  cases   in 


which  d  is  fourth,  but  neither  a,  b,  nor  c  in  its  proper  place  is 
\n-l-2\n-2  +  \n-S-hn-2-2\n-S  +  |  n  -  41,    that   is 

1/1  —  1  —  3  \n  —  2  +  3  \n  —  S  —  \n  —  4*.     And  generally  the  number 

of  cases  in  which  the  m^^  card  is  in  its  proper  place,  while  none 
of  its  predecessors  is  in  its  proper  place,  is 

\n-l  -  (m  -  1)  1 71-2  +  ^ -^ ^  \n-S 


{m  -1)  (m-  2)  (m-3) 


wt-l 


w  —  m. 


^  ,71-4  + +  (-1) 

"We  may  supply  a  step  here  in  the  process  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli, 
by  shewing  the  truth  of  this  result  by  induction.  Let  -v/r  (771,  n) 
denote  the  number  of  cases  in  which  the  m"'  card  is  the  first  that 
occurs  in  its  right  place ;  we  have  to  trace  the  connexion  between 
^jr  (m,  n)  and  yjr  {m  +  1,  n).  The  number  of  cases  in  which  the 
{m  +  l)**^  card  is  in  its  right  place  while  none  of  the  cards  between 
h  and  the  W2*'^  card,  both  inclusive,  is  in  its  right  place,  is  '^^  (m,  n). 
From  this  number  we  must  reject  all  those  cases  in  which  a  is  in  its 
right  place,  and  thus  we  shall  obtain  yjr  {in  +  1,  n).  The  cases  to 
be  rejected  are  in  number  '^  {m,  n  —  1).     Thus 

y^  (in  +  1,  w)  =  i/r  {in,  n)  —  yfr  {in,  n  —  1). 

Hence  we  can  shew  that  the  form  assigned  by  Nicolas  Bernoulli 
to  -^/r  (m,  n)  is  universally  true. 

Thus  if  a  person  undertakes  that  the  m*^  card  shall  be  the  first 
that  is  in  its  right  place,  the  number  of  cases  favourable  to  him  is 

'^  (m,  n),  and  therefore  his  chance  is       .  ' — -  , 

\n 

If  he  undertakes  that  at  least  one  card  shall  be  in  its  right 

place,  we  obtain   the   number  of  favourable  cases  by  summing 

^jr  (m,  n)  for  all  values  of  m  from  1  to  n  both  inclusive :  the  chance 

is  found  by  dividing  this  sum  by  [n. 

Hence  we  shall  obtain  for  the  chance  that  at  least  one  card  is 
in  its  right  place, 

i_l+i_l,     ,  (- 1)- 

2     [3     li^'"^       \n      ' 


MONTilORT.  93 

"We  may  observe  that  if  we  subtract  the  last  expression  from 
unity  we  obtain  the  chance  that  no  card  is  in  its  right  place.  Hence 
if  (f>  (n)  denote  the  number  of  cases  in  which  no  card  is  in  its  right 
place,  we  obtain 

162.  The  game  which  Montmort  calls  Treize  has  sometimes 
been  called  Rencontre.  The  problem  which  is  here  introduced  for 
the  first  time  has  been  generalised  and  discussed  by  the  following 
writers  :  De  Moivre,  Doctrine  of  Chances,  pages  109 — 117.  Euler, 
Hist,  de  T Acad.... Berlin,  for  1751.  Lambert,  Kouveaux  Memoires 
de  T Acad.  ...  Berlin,  for  1771.  Laplace,  TJieorie  . . .  des  Proh. 
pages  217 — 225.  Michaelis,  Memoire  sur  la  prohahilite  du  jeu  de 
rencontre,  Berlin,  1846. 

163.  Pages  148 — 156  of  Montmort  relate  to  the  game  of  Bas- 
sette.  This  is  one  of  the  most  celebrated  of  the  old  games :  it 
bears  a  great  resemblance  to  Pharaon. 

As  we  have  already  stated,  this  game  was  discussed  by  James 
Bernoulli,  who  summed  up  his  results  in  the  form  of  six  tables ; 
see  Art.  119.  The  most  imi^ortant  of  these  tables  is  in  the  fourth, 
which  is  in  effect  also  reproduced  in  De  Moivre's  investigations. 
The  reader  who  wishes  to  obtain  a  notion  of  the  game  may  con- 
sult De  Moivre's  Doctrine  of  Chances,  pages  69 — 77. 

164.  James  Bernoulli  and  De  Moivre  confine  themselves  to 
the  case  of  a  common  pack  of  cards,  so  that  a  particular  card,  an 
ace  for  example,  cannot  occur  more  than  four  times.  Montmort 
however,  considers  the  subject  more  generally,  and  gives  formulae 
for  a  pack  of  cards  consisting  of  any  number  of  suits.  Montmort 
gives  a  general  formula  on  his  page  153  which  is  new  in  his  second 
edition.  The  quantity  which  De  Moivre  denotes  by  y  and  puts 
equal  to  ^  is  taken  to  be  |  by  Montmort. 

Montmort  gives  a  numerical  table  of  the  advantage  of  the 
Banker  at  Bassette.  In  the  second  edition  some  fractions  are 
left  unreduced  which  were  reduced  to  their  lowest  terms  in  the 
first  edition,  the  object  of  the   change  being  jDrobably  to    allow 


94  MONTMORT. 

the  law  of  formation  to  be  more  readily  perceived.  The  last 
fraction,  given  in  the  table  was  wrong  in  the  first  edition  ;  see 
Montmort's  page  803.  It  would  be  advisable  to  multiply  both 
numerator  and  denominator  of  this  fraction  by  12  to  maintain 
uniformity  in  the  table. 

165.  Montmort  devotes  his  pages  157 — 172  to  some  pro- 
blems respecting  games  which  are  not  entirely  games  of  chance. 
He  gives  some  preliminary  remarks  to  shew  that  the  complete 
discussion  of  such  games  is  too  laborious  and  complex  for  our 
powers  of  analysis ;  he  therefore  restricts  himself  to  some  special 
problems  relating  to  the  games. 

The  games  are  not  described,  so  that  it  would  be  difficult  to 
undertake  an  examination  of  Montmort's  investigations.  Two  of 
the  problems,  namely,  those  relating  to  the  game  of  Piquet,  are 
given  by  De  Moivre  with  more  detail  than  by  Montmort  ;  see 
Doctrine  of  Chances,  page  179.  These  problems  are  simple  exer- 
cises in  combinations ;  and  it  would  appear  that  all  Montmort's 
other  problems  in  this  part  of  his  book  are  of  a  similar  kind,  pre- 
senting no  difficulty  except  that  arising  from  a  want  of  familiarity 
with  the  undescribed  games  to  which  they  belong. 

166.  Montmort's  third  part  occupies  pages  173  —  215  ;  it 
relates  to  games  of  chance  involving  dice.  This  part  is  almost 
identically  repeated  from  the  first  edition. 

The  first  game  is  called  Qicinqiienove ;  it  is  described,  and  a 
calculation  given  of  the  disadvantage  of  a  player.  The  second 
game  is  called  Hazard;  this  is  also  described,  and  a  calculation 
given  of  the  disadvantage  of  the  player  who  holds  the  dice.  This 
game  is  discussed  by  De  Moivre;  see  his  pages  160 — 166.  The 
third  game  is  cslled  Fs2:>erance ;  it  is  described  and  a  particular 
case  of  it  with  three  players  is  calculated.  The  calculation  is 
extremely  laborious,  and  the  chances  of  the  three  players  are 
represented  by  three  fractions,  the  common  denominator  being  a 
number  of  twenty  figures.  Then  follow  games  called  Trois  Dez, 
Passe-dix,  Rafle ;  these  are  described  somewhat  obscurely,  and 
problems  respecting  them  are  solved ;  Raffling  is  discussed  by  De 
Moivre;  see  pages  166 — 172  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances. 


MONTMORT.  95 

167.  The  last  game  is  called  Le  Jeu  des  Koyaux,  which 
Montmort  says  the  Baron  de  la  Hontan  had  found  to  be  in  use 
among  the  savages  of  Canada ;  see  Montmort's  pages  xii  and  213. 
The  game  is  thus  described, 

On  y  joue  avec  huit  noyaux  noirs  d'un  cote  et  blancs  de  I'autre  :  on 
jette  les  noyaux  en  Fair  :  alors  si  les  noirs  se  trouvent  impairs,  celui  qui 
a  jette  les  noyaux  gagne  ce  que  I'autre  Joueur  a  uiis  au  jeu  :  S'ils  se 
trouvent  ou  tous  noirs  ou  tous  blancs,  il  en  gagne  le  double ;  et  hors  de 
ces  deux  cas  il  perd  sa  mise. 

Suppose  eight  dice  each  having  only  two  faces,  one  face  black 
and  one  white ;  let  them  be  thrown  up  at  random.  There  are 
then  T,  that  is  256,  equally  possible  cases.  It  will  be  found  that 
there  are  8  cases  for  one  black  and  seven  white,  5Q  cases  for  three 
black  and  five  white,  28  cases  for  two  black  and  six  white,  and 
70  cases  for  four  black  and  four  white  ;  and  there  is  only  one  case 
for  all  black.  Thus  if  the  whole  stake  be  denoted  by  A,  the  chance 
of  the  player  who  throws  the  dice  is 

_L  j  (8  +  8  +  56  +  50)  .4  +  2  (.1  +  I  A)  |  , 

and  the  chance  of  the  other  player  is 

2^^1(28  +  28  +  70)^  +  2(0-1.1)1. 

131  125 

The  former  is  equal  to  tt^.  A,  and  the  latter  to  77^  A, 

2ob  loij 

Montmort  says  that  the  problem  was  proposed  to  him  by  a 
lady  who  gave  him  almost  instantly  a  correct  solution  of  it ;  but 
he  proceeds  very  rudely  to  depreciate  the  lady's  solution  by  in- 
sinuating that  it  was  only  correct  by  accident,  for  her  method  was 
restricted  to  the  case  in  which  there  were  only  two  faces  on  each 
of  the  dice  :  Montmort  then  proposes  a  similar  problem  in  which 
each  of  the  dice  has  ybi^r  faces. 

Montmort  should  have  recorded  the  name  of  the  only  lady  who 
has  contributed  to  the  Theory  of  Probability. 


96  MONTMORT. 

168.  The  fourth  part  of  Montmort's  book  occupies  pages 
216 — 282  ;  it  contains  the  solution  of  various  problems  respecting 
chances,  and  in  particular  of  the  five  proposed  by  Huygens  in 
1657  ;  see  Art.  35.  This  part  of  the  work  extends  to  about  double 
the  length  of  the  corresponding  part  in  the  first  edition. 

169.  Montmort's  solution  of  Hujgens's  first  problem  is  similar 
to  that  given  by  James  Bernoulli.  The  first  few  lines  of  Mont- 
mort's Remarque  on  his  page  217  are  not  in  his  first  edition  ;  they 
strongly  resemble  some  lines  in  the  Ars  Coiijectandi,  page  51. 
But  Montmort  does  not  refer  to  the  latter  work,  either  in  his 
preface  or  elsewhere,  although  it  appeared  before  his  own  second 
edition;  the  interval  however  between  the  two  publications  may 
have  been  very  small,  and  so  perhaps  Montmort  had  not  seen  the 
Ars  Conjectandi  until  after  his  own  work  had  been  completely 
printed. 

The  solution  of  Huygens's  fifth  problem  is  very  laborious,  and 
inferior  to  that  given  by  James  Bernoulli ;  and  Montmort  him- 
self admits  that  he  had  not  adopted  the  best  method  ;  see  his 
page  223. 

The  solutions  of  Huygens's  problems  which  Montmort  gave 
in  his  first  edition  received  the  benefit  of  some  observations  by 
John  Bernoulli  ;  these  are  printed  in  Montmort's  fifth  part, 
pages  292 — 294,  and  by  the  aid  of  them  the  solutions  in  the  second 
edition  were  improved :  but  Montmort's  discussions  of  the  pro- 
blems remain  still  far  less  elaborate  than  those  of  James  Bernoulli. 

170.  Montmort  next  takes  two  problems  which  amount  to 
finding  the  value  of  an  annuity,  allowing  compound  interest. 
Then  he  proceeds  to  the  problem  of  which  a  particular  example 
is  to  find  in  how  many  throws  with  a  single  die  it  will  be  an 
even  chance  to  throw  a  six. 

171.  Montmort  now  devotes  his  pages  232 — 248  to  the  Pro- 
blem of  Points.  He  reprints  Pascal's  letter  of  August  14th,  1654, 
to  which  we  have  alluded  in  Art.  16,  and  then  he  adds,  page  241, 

Le  respect  que  nous  avons  pour  la  reputation  et  pour  la  memoire  de 
M.  Pascal,  ne  nous  permet  pas  de  faire  remarquer  ici  en  detiiil  toutes 


MONTMORT.  97 

les  fautes  de  raisonnement  qui  sont  dans  cette  Lettre ;  il  nous  suffira 
d'avertir  que  la  cause  de  son  erreur  est  de  n'avoir  point  d'egard  aux 
divers  arrangemens  des  lettres. 

Montmort's  words  seem  to  imply  that  Pascal's  letter  contains 
a  large  amount  of  error ;  we  have,  however,  only  the  single  fun- 
damental inaccuracy  which  Fermat  corrected,  as  we  have  shewTi  in 
Art.  19,  and  the  inference  that  it  was  not  allowaVjle  to  suppose 
that  a  certain  number  of  trials  will  necessarily  be  made;  see  Art.  18. 

172.  Montmort  gives  for  the  first  time  two  formulae  either  of 
which  is  a  complete  solution  of  the  Problem  of  Points  when  there 
are  two  players,  taking  into  account  difference  of  skill.  We  will 
exhibit  these  formulae  in  modern  notation.  Suppose  that  A  wants 
711  points  and  B  wants  n  points ;  so  that  the  game  will  be  neces- 
sarily decided  in  m-\-n—l  trials  ;  \etm  +  n—l  =  r.  Let  p  denote 
A's  skill,  that  is  his  chance  of  winning  in  a  single  trial,  and  let 
q  denote  J5's  skill  ;  so  that  p  +  q  =  l. 

Then  ^'s  chance  of  winning  the  game  is 

pr^     r-i    _^r(r-l)  ,_^ +   ,— ,^^— fi^V"; 

^"^^         1.2^  [m  I  ??  —  1 

and  Bs  chance  of  winning  the  game  is 

q'+rr'p+^^-^Y^  2-p=+ +  ^^zi^  ?>"'-  ■ 

This  is  the  first  formula.  According  to  the  second  formula  J's 
chance  of  winning  the  game  is 

m  f  1   .  m  (m  +  1)   «  ,  ,         1/ ""  i_       ^K-i  1  . 


and  B's  chance  of  winning  the  game  is 

„  f-  ,  7^  (n  +  1)    „  ,  l^~^        ,,--'  I 

^  r-^^'^"^  172  ^+ ^\m-i.n-ij   r 

Montmort  demonstrates  the  truth  of  these  formulae,  but  we 
need  not  crive  the  demonstrations  here  as  they  will  be  found  in 
elementary  works;  see  Algebra,  Chapter  Llli. 

173.  In  Montmort's  first  edition  he  had  confined  himself 
to  the  case  of  equal  skill  and  had  given  only  the  first  formula, 


93  MONTMORT. 

SO  that  he  had  not  really  advanced  beyond  Pascal,  although  the 
formula  would  be  more  convenient  than  the  use  of  the  Arith- 
metical Triangle ;  see  Art.  23.  The  first  formula  for  the  case 
of  unequal  skill  was  communicated  to  Montmort  by  John  Ber- 
noulli in  a  letter  dated  March  17th,  1710 ;  see  Montmort's  page  295. 
As  we  have  already  stated  the  formula  was  known  to  James 
BernouUi;  see  Art.  113.  The  second  formula  for  the  Problem  of 
Points  must  be  assigned  to  Montmort  himself,  for  it  now  appears 
before  us  for  the  first  time. 

174.     It  will  be  interesting  to  make  some  comparison  between 
the  two  formulae  given  in  Art.  172. 

It  may  be  shewn  that  we  have  identically 

p'  +  rp''q-h    \  ,^  ' J)    <i  +...  +  -—::::     rV  9. 


r^V^  if-^  +  m  (2>  +  ^)--^  +  !!^!i±i)  (^  +  g)'-'-/  + 


r  —  1 


m  —  1    n 


This  may  be  shewn  by  picking  out  the  coefficients  of  the 
various  powers  of  ^  in  the  expression  on  the  right-hand  side, 
making  use  of  the  relations  presented  by  the  identity 

(1  -  j)-"-»'(l- 2)-=  (1 -?)"'. 

Thus  we  see  that  \i  'p-\-  c[  be  equal  to  unity  the  two  expres- 
sions given  in  Art.  172  for  ^'s  chance  are  numerically  equal. 

175.  If  however  ^  +  ^^  be  not  equal  to  unity  the  two  expres- 
sions given  in  Art.  172  for  ^'s  chance  are  not  numerically  equal. 
If  we  suppose  jy-^-  q  less  than  unity,  we  can  give  the  following  in- 
terpretation to  the  formulae.  Suppose  that  A 's  chance  of  winning 
in  a  single  trial  is  jp,  and  i?'s  chance  is  q,  and  that  there  is  the 
chance  ^—jp  —  q  that  it  is  a  drawn  contest. 

Then  the  formula 


mi,  w  (??z  +  1)    „  \r  —\ 

^  1.2       -^  m— 1^1  —  1^ 


MONTMORT.  09 

expresses  the  chance  that  A  shall  win  m  points  before  either  a 
single  drawn  contest  occurs,  or  B  wins  n  points. 

This  is  easily  seen  by  examining  the  reasoning  by  which  the 
formula  is  established  in  the  case  when  p  -{-  q  is  equal  to  unity. 

But  the  formula 

expresses  the  chance  that  A  shall  win  m  points  out  of  r,  on  the 
condition  that  r  trials  are  to  be  made,  and  that  A  is  not  to  be  con- 
sidered to  have  won  if  a  drawn  contest  should  occur  even  after  he 
has  won  his  m  points. 

This  follows  from  the  fact  that  if  we  expand  (2^  +  q  +  1  —p  —  qY 
in  powers  of  j^,  q,  1  —  ^  —  5',  a  term  such  as  Cj^^q^il  —2^  —  qy  ex- 
presses the  chance  that  A  wins  p  points,  B  wins  a  points,  and  r 
contests  are  drawn. 

Or  we  may  treat  this  second  case  by  using  the  transformation 
in  Art.  174.  Then  we  see  that  {p  +  qy"^  expresses  the  chance 
that  there  shall  be  no  dra^\Ti  contest  after  the  m  points  which  A  is 
supposed  to  have  won  ;  {p-{-  ^)'""'"^  expresses  the  chance  that  there 
shall  be  no  drawn  contest  after  the  m  points  which  A  is  supposed 
to  have  won,  and  the  single  point  which  B  is  supposed  to  have 
won  ;  and  so  on. 

176.  Montmort  thinks  it  might  be  easily  imagined  that  the 
chances  of  A  and  B,  if  they  respectivel}'  want  km  and  Jen  points, 
would  be  the  same  as  if  they  respectively  wanted  m  and  71  points ; 
but  this  he  says  is  not  the  case  ;  see  his  page  24? 7.  He  seems  to 
assert  that  as  k  increases  the  chance  of  the  player  of  greater  skill 
necessarily  increases  with  it.    He  does  not  however  demonstrate  this. 

We  know  by  Bernoulli's  theorem  that  if  the  number  of  trials 
be  made  large  enough,  there  is  a  very  high  probability  that  the 
number  of  points  won  by  each  player  respectively  will  be  nearly  in 
the  ratio  of  his  skill ;  so  that  if  the  ratio  ofm  to  n  be  less  than  that 
of  the  skill  of  A  to  the  skill  of  B,  we  can,  by  increasing  k,  obtain  as 
great  a  probability  as  we  please  that  A  will  win  km  points  before 
B  wins  hi  points. 

Montmort  probably  implies,  though  he  does  not  state,  the  con- 
dition which  we  have  put  in  Italics. 

7—2 


1 00  MONTMORT. 

177.  Montmort  devotes  his  pages  248 — 257  to  the  discussion 
of  a  game  of  Bowls,  which  leads  to  a  problem  resembling  the  Pro- 
blem of  Points.  The  problem  was  started  by  De  Moivre  in  his 
Be  Mensura  Sortis ;  see  Montmort,  page  866,  and  the  Doctrine  of 
Chances,  page  121.  De  Moivre  had  supposed  the  players  to  be  of 
equal  skill,  and  each  to  have  the  same  number  of  balls  ;  Montmort 
generalised  the  problem  by  supposing  players  of  unequal  skill  and 
having  unequal  numbers  of  balls.  Thus  the  problem  was  not  in 
Montmort's  first  edition. 

Montmort  gives  on  his  page  256  a  simple  example  of  a  solution 
of  a  problem  which  appears  very  plausible,  but  which  is  incorrect. 
Suppose  A  plays  with  one  bowl  and  B  with  two  bowls ;  required 
their  respective  chances  in  one  trial,  assuming  equal  skill. 
Considering  that  any  one   of  the  three  bowls  is  as  likely  as  the 

.2  .1 

others  to  be  first,  the  chance  of  ^  is  ^r  and  that  of  ^  is  -  .     But  by 

3  3  -^ 

the  incorrect  solution  Montmort  arrives  at  a  different  result.     For 

suppose  A   to  have  delivered  his  bowl.     Then  B  has  the  chance 

^  with  his  first  bowl  of  beating  A ;  and  the  chance  -  x  ^  of  failing 
with  his  first  bowl  and  being  successful  with  his  second.  Thus  ^'s 
chance  appears  to  be  -  •  Montmort  considers  the  error  of  this  so- 
lution to  lie  in  the  assumption  that  when  B  has  failed  to  beat  A 
with  his  first  bowl  it  is  still  an  even  chance  that  he  will  beat  A  with 
his  second  bowl :  for  the  fact  that  B  failed  with  his  first  bowl 
suggests  that  ^'s  bowl  has  a  position  better  than  the  average,  so 
that  jB's  chance  of  success  with  his  second  bowl  becomes  less  than 
an  even  chance. 

178.  Montmort  then  takes  four  problems  in  succession  of 
trifling  importance.  The  first  relates  to  a  lottery  which  was  started 
in  Paris  in  1710,  in  which  the  projector  had  offered  to  the  public 
terms  which  were  very  disadvantageous  to  himself  The  second  is 
an  easy  exercise  in  combinations.  The  third  relates  to  a  game 
called  Le  Jeu  des  Oublieux.  The  fourth  is  an  extension  of 
Huygens's  eleventh  problem,  and  is  also  given  in  the  Ars  Conjee- 
tandi,  page  34.    These  four  problems  are  new  in  the  second  edition. 


MOXTMORT.  101 

179.  Montmort  now  passes  to  a  problem  of  a  more  important 
character  which  occupies  his  pages  268 — 277,  and  which  is  also 
new  in  the  second  edition;  it  relates  to  the  Duration  of  Play; 
see  Art.  107. 

Suppose  A.  to  have  m  counters  and  i?  to  have  n  counters  ;  let 
their  chances  of  winning  a  single  game  be  as  a  to  ^  ;  the  loser  in 
each  game  is  to  give  a  counter  to  his  adversary  :  required  the  chance 
that  A  will  have  won  all  5's  counters  on  or  before  the  x^^  game. 

This  is  the  most  difficult  problem  which  had  as  yet  been  solved 
in  the  sulyect.    Montmort's  formula  is  given  on  his  pages  268,  269. 

180.  The  history  of  this  problem  up  to  the  current  date  will 
be  found  by  comparing  the  following  pages  of  Montmort's  book, 
275,  309,  315,  324,  344,  368,  375,  380. 

It  appears  that  Montmort  worked  at  the  problem  and  also 
asked  Nicolas  Bernoulli  to  try  it.  Nicolas  Bernoulli  sent  a 
solution  to  Montmort,  which  Montmort  said  he  admired  but 
could  not  understand,  and  he  thought  his  o^^TL  method  of  investi- 
gation and  that  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli  must  be  very  different :  but 
after  explanations  received  from  Nicolas  Bernoulli,  Montmort 
came  to  the  conclusion  that  the  methods  were  the  same.  Before 
however  the  publication  of  Montmort's  second  edition,  De  Moi\Te 
had  solved  the  problem  in  a  different  manner  in  the  De  Mensura 
Sortis. 

181.  The  general  problem  of  the  Duration  of  Play  was  studied 
by  De  Moivre  with  great  acuteness  and  success ;  indeed  his  inves- 
tigation forms  one  of  his  chief  contributions  to  the  subject. 

He  refers  in  the  following  words  to  Nicolas  Bernoulli  and 
Montmort : 

Monsieur  de  Monniort^  in  the  Second  Edition  of  his  Book  of  Chances, 
having  given  a  very  handsom  Solution  of  the  Problem  relating  to  the 
duration  of  Play,  (which  Solution  is  coincident  with  that  of  Monsieur 
Nicolas  Bemoully,  to  be  seen  in  that  Book)  and  the  demonstration  of  it 
being  very  naturally  deduced  from  our  first  Solution  of  the  foregoing 
Problem,  I  thought  the  Reader  would  be  well  pleased  to  see  it  trans- 
ferred to  this  place. 

Doctrine  of  Chances;  first  edition,  page  122. 


J  02  MONTMORT. 

...the  Solution  of  Mr  Nicolas  Bernoulli  beiog  very  much  crouded 
with  Symbols,  and  the  verbal  Explication  of  them  too  scanty,  I  own 
I  did  not  understand  it  thoroughly,  which  obliged  me  to  consider  Mr. 
de  Monimort^s  Solution  with  very  great  attention :  I  found  indeed  that 
he  was  very  plain,  but  to  my  great  surpriza  I  found  him  very  erroneous; 
still  in  my  Doctrine  of  Chances  I  printed  that  Solution,  but  rectified 
and  ascribed  it  to  Mr.  de  Monmort,  without  the  least  intimation  of  any 
alterations  made  by  me ;  but  as  I  had  no  thanks  for  so  doing,  I  resume 
my  right,  and  now  print  it  as  my  own — 

Doctrine  of  Chances;  second  edition  page  181,  third  edition,  page  211. 

The  language  of  De  Moivre  in  his  second  and  third  editions 
would  seem  to  imply  that  the  solutions  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli  and 
Montmort  are  different ;  but  they  are  really  coincident,  as  De 
Moivre  had  himself  stated  in  his  first  edition.  The  statement  that 
Montmort's  solution  is  very  erroneous,  is  unjustly  severe ;  Mont- 
mort has  given  his  formula  without  proper  precaution,  but  his 
example  which  immediately  follows  shews  that  he  was  right  him- 
self and  would  serve  to  guide  his  readers.  The  second  edition  of 
the  Doctrine  of  Chances  appeared  nearly  twenty  years  after  the 
death  of  Montmort ;  and  the  change  in  De  Moivre's  language 
respecting  him  seems  therefore  especially  ungenerous. 

182.  We  shall  not  here  give  Montmort's  general  solution  of 
the  Problem  of  the  Duration  of  Play ;  we  shall  have  a  better 
opportunity  of  noticing  it  in  connexion  with  De  Moivre's  investiga- 
tions. We  will  make  three  remarks  which  may  be  of  service  to 
any  student  who  examines  Montmort's  own  work. 

Montmort's  general  ^statement  on  his  pages  2G8,  269,  might 
easily  mislead ;  the  example  at  the  end  of  page  269  is  a  safer 
guide.  If  the  statement  were  literally  followed,  the  second  line  in 
the  example  would  consist  of  as  many  terms  as  the  first  line,  the 
fourth  of  as  many  terms  as  the  third,  and  the  sixth  of  as  many 
terms  as  the  fifth;  but  this  would  be  wrong,  shewing  that  the 
general  statement  is  not  literally  accurate. 

Montmort's  explanation  at  the  end  of  his  page  270,  and  the  be- 
ginning of  his  page  271,  is  not  satisfactory.  It  is  not  true  as  he 
intimates,  that  the  four  letters  a  and  the  eleven  letters  h  must  be 


MONTMORT.  IQ: 


SO  arranged  that  only  a  single  h  is  to  come  among  the  four  letters 
a :  we  might  have  such  an  arrangement  as  aaahhhhhhhhhhha.  We 
shall  return  to    this    point  in   our    account    of  De    Moivi'e's   in- 


vestigations. 


On  his  page  272  Montmort  gives  a  rule  deduced  from  his 
formula ;  he  ought  to  state  that  the  rule  assumes  that  the  players 
are  of  equal  skill :  his  rule  also  assumes  that  p  —  m  is  an  even 
number. 

183.  On  his  pages  275,  276  Montmort  gives  without  demon- 
stration results  for  two  special  cases. 

(1)     Suppose  that  there  are  two  players  of  equal  skill,  and  that 

each  starts  with  two  counters ;  then  1  —  ^-  is  the  chance  that  the 

match  will  be  ended  in  2x  games  at  most.  The  result  may  be  de- 
duced from  Montmort's  general  expression.  A  property  of  the 
Binomial  Coefficients  is  involved  which  we  may  briefly  indicate. 

Let  Wj,  u^,  u^,  ...  denote  the  successive  terms  in  the  expansion 
of  (I  +  l)'"^.     Let  >S'  denote  the  sum  of  the  following  series 

w.  +  ^ii.-i+  Ux-i+  0  +  u,_,+  2it,_,+  u,_,+  0  +  w^_3+  ... 
Then  shall  S=r'-'-2'-\ 

For  let  V,  denote  the  r^^  term  in  the  expansion  of  (1  +  1)"''"S  and 
lOy  the  ?'"'  term  in  the  expansion  of  (1  +  1)"''"^     Then 

t'y  t/j.  "t"    I-  r—Xf 

Employ  the  former  transformation  in  the  odd  terms  of  our  pro- 
posed series,  and  the  latter  in  the  even  terms ;  thus  we  find  that 
the  proposed  series  becomes 

'^x  +  ^.r-1  +  ^'x-2  +  ^.r-3  +  ^x--4  +   '  '  ' 
+  2  [W^_^  -h  2W^_^  +  IC,_^  +  0  +  10, _,  +  ...}. 

The  first  of  these  two  series  is  equal  to  ^  (1  +  I)'''"' ;  and  the 

second  is  a  series  of  the  same  kind  as  that  which  we  wish  to  sum 
with  X  chanced  into  x-1.  Thus  we  can  finish  the  demonstration 
hy  induction ;  for  obviously 


101  MONTMORT. 

(2)     Next  suppose  that  each  player  starts  with  three  counters  ; 
ox 

then  1  —  —  is  the  chance  that  the  match  will  be  ended  in  2ic  +  1 

games  at  most.  This  result  had  in  fact  been  given  by  Montmort  in 
his  first  edition,  page  184.  It  may  be  deduced  from  Montmort's 
general  expression,  and  involves  a  property  of  the  Binomial  Coeffi- 
cients which  we  will  briefly  indicate. 

Let  w^,  u^,  u^, ...  denote  the  successive  term-;  in  the  expansion 
of  (1  +  iy'^\     Let  S  denote  the  sum  of  the  following  series 

Then  shall  8=2'"'-  3^. 

If  w^  denote  the  r**^  term  in  the  expansion  of  (1  +  1)'^''"^  we  can 
shew  that 

w^  +  2m^_i  +  2w^_2  +  u^_s 

+  S  (2^,_i  +  2w;^_2  +  2w;^_3  +  2(7^ J. 

By  performing  a  similar  transformation  on   every  successive 
four  significant  terms  of  the  original  series  we  transform  it  into 

2  (1  +  1)'''"^  +  3S,  where  2  is  a  series  like  S  with  x  changed  into 

x-1.     Thus 

8  =  2^^-2  +  32. 

Hence  by  induction  we  find  that  /S^=  2^""  -  S''. 

184.     Suppose  the  players  of  equal  skill,  and  that  each  starts 

with  the  same  odd  number  of  counters,  say  m ;  let  /=  '^'^^ , 

Then  Montmort  says,  on  his  page  276,  that  we  may  wager  with 
adva.ntage  that  the  match  will  be  concluded  in  3/'  -  3/+  1  trials. 
Montmort  does  not  shew  how  he  arrived  at  this  approximation. 

The   expression   may  be  put  in  the  form  \m'^\,     De  Moivre 

4  4 

spoke  favourably  of  this  approximation  on  page  148  of  his  first  edi- 
tion; he  says,  "Now  Mr  de  Montmort  having  with  great  Sagacity 
discovered  that  Analogy,  in  the  case  of  an  equal  and  Odd  number 
of  Stakes,   on   supposition  of  an  equality  of  Skill  between  the 


MONTMORT.  105 

Gamesters..."  In  his  second  and  third  editions  De  Moivre  with- 
drew this  commendation,  and  says  respecting  the  rule  "  Which  tho' 
near  the  Truth  in  small  numbers,  yet  is  very  defective  in  large 
ones,  for  it  may  be  proved  that  the  number  of  Games  found  by  his 
Expression,  far  from  being  above  what  is  requisite  is  really  below 
it."     Doctrine  of  Chances,  third  edition,  page  218. 

De  Moivre  takes  for  an  example  m  =  45  ;  and  calculates  by  his 
own  mode  of  approximation  that  about  1531  games  are  requisite 
in  order  that  it  may  be  an  even  chance  that  the  match  will  be 
concluded  ;  Montmort's  rule  would  assign  1519  games.  We  should 
differ  here  with  De  Moivre,  and  consider  that  the  results  are 
rather  remarkable  for  their  near  agreement  than  for  their  dis- 
crepancy. 

The  problem  of  the  Duration  of  Play  is  fully  discussed  by 
Laplace,  Theorie...des  Proh.  pages  225 — 238. 

185.  Montmort  gives  some  numerical  results  for  a  simple 
problem  on  his  page  277.  Suppose  in  the  problem  of  Art.  107  that 
the  two  players  are  of  equal  skill,  each  having  originally  n  counters. 
Proceeding  as  in  that  Article,  we  have 

Hence  we  find  u^=  Cx+  C^,  where  C  and  (7^  are  arbitraiy  con- 
stants.    To  determine  them  we  have 

^0=0,  %„  =  !; 

hence  finally,  w«  =  ^  • 

Montmort's  example  is  for  ?i  =  6 ;  he  gave  it  in  his  first  edition, 
page  178.  He  did  not  however  appear  to  have  observed  the  gene- 
ral law,  at  which  John  Bernoulli  expressed  his  sm-prise  ;  see  Mont- 
mort's page  295. 

186.  Montmort  now  proposes  on  pages  278 — 282  four  pro- 
blems for  solution ;  they  were  originally  given  at  the  end  of  the 
first  edition. 

The  first  problem  is  sur  le  Jeu  dii  Treize.  It  is  not  obvious 
why  this  problem  is  repeated,  for  Montmort  stated  the  results  on 
his  pages  130 — 143,  and  demonstrations  by  Nicolas  Bernoulli  are 
given  on  pages  301,  302. 


lOG  MONTMORT. 

The  second  problem  is  sur  le  Jen  appelle  le  Her;  a  discussion 
respecting  this  problem  runs  through  the  correspondence  between 
Montmort  and  Nicolas  Bernoulli.  See  Montmort's  pages  321,  334, 
338,  348,  361,  376,  400,  402,  403,  409,  413.  We  will  return  to 
this  problem  in  Art.  187. 

The  third  problem  is  sur  le  Jeu  de  la  Ferme  ;  it  is  not  referred 
to  again  in  the  book. 

The  fourth  Problem  is  sur  le  Jeu  des  Tas.  We  will  return  to 
this  problem  in  Art.  191. 

Montmort's  language  in  his  Avertisseynent,  page  xxv,  leads  to  the 
expectation  that  solutions  of  all  the  four  problems  will  be  found 
in  the  book,  whereas  only  the  first  is  solved,  and  indeed  Montmort 
himself  seems  not  to  have  solved  the  others ;  see  his  page  321. 

187.  It  may  be  advisable  to  give  some  account  of  the  discus- 
sion respecting  the  game  called  Her.  The  game  is  described  by 
Montmort  as  played  by  several  persons  ;  but  the  discussion  was 
confined  to  the  case  of  two  players,  and  we  will  adopt  this 
limitation. 

Peter  holds  a  common  pack  of  cards  ;  he  gives  a  card  at  random 
to  Paul  and  takes  one  himself;  the  main  object  is  for  each  to 
obtain  a  higher  card  than  his  adversary.  The  order  of  value  is 
ace,  tiuo,  three,  ...  ten.  Knave,  Queen,  Kmg. 

Now  if  Paul  is  not  content  with  his  card  he  may  compel  Peter 
to  change  with  him  ;  but  if  Peter  has  a  King  he  is  allowed  to 
retain  it.  If  Peter  is  not  content  with  the  card  which  he  at  first 
obtained,  or  which  he  has  been  compelled  to  receive  from  Paul,  he 
is  allowed  to  change  it  for  another  taken  out  of  the  pack  at 
random  ;  but  if  the  card  he  then  draws  is  a  King  he  is  not  allowed 
to  have  it,  but  must  retain  the  card  with  which  he  was  dissatisfied. 
If  Paul  and  Peter  finally  have  cards  of  the  same  value  Paul  is 
considered  to  lose. 

188.  The  problem  involved  amounts  to  a  determination  of  the 
relative  chances  of  Peter  and  Paul ;  and  this  depends  on  their 
using  or  declining  their  rights  of  changing  their  cards.  Montmort 
communicated  the  problem  to  two  of  his  friends,  namely  Walde- 
grave,  of  whom  we  hear  again,  and  a  person  who  is  called  some- 


MONTMORT.  107 

times  M.  I'Abbe  de  Monsoury  and  sometimes  M.  TAbbe  d'Orbais. 
These  two  persons  differed  with  Nicolas  Bernoulli  respecting  a 
point  in  the  problem  ;  Nicolas  Bernoulli  asserted  that  in  a  certain 
contingency  of  the  game  each  player  ought  to  take  a  certain  course 
out  of  two  which  were  open  to  him ;  the  other  two  persons  con- 
tended that  it  was  not  certain  that  one  of  the  courses  ought  to  be 
preferred  to  the  other. 

Montmort  himself  scarcely  interfered  until  the  end  of  the  cor- 
respondence, when  he  intimated  that  his  opinion  was  contrary  to 
that  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli ;  it  would  seem  that  the  latter  intended 
to  produce  a  fuller  explanation  of  his  views,  but  the  corresj)ondence 
closes  without  it. 

189.  We  will  give  some  details  in  order  to  shew  the  nature  of 
the  dispute. 

It  will  naturally  occur  to  the  reader  that  one  general  principle 
must  hold,  namely,  that  if  a  player  has  obtained  a  high  card  it  will 
be  prudent  for  him  to  rest  content  with  it  and  not  to  run  the 
risk  involved  in  changing  .that  card  for  another.  For  example,  it 
appears  to  be  tacitly  allowed  by  the  disputants  that  if  Paid  has 
obtained  an  ei(jht,  or  a  higher  card,  he  will  remain  content  with  it, 
and  not  compel  Peter  to  change  with  him  ;  and,  on  the  other 
hand,  if  Paul  has  obtained  a  six,  or  a  lower  card,  he  will  compel 
Peter  to  change.  The  dispute  turns  on  what  Paul  should  do  if 
he  has  obtained  a  seven.  The  numerical  data  for  discussino-  this 
case  v/ill  be  found  on  Montmort's  page  339  ;  we  will  reproduce 
them  with  some  explanation  of  the  process  by  which  thev  are 
obtained. 

I.  Paul  has  a  seven ;  required  his  chance  if  he  compels  Peter 
to  change. 

Supposing  Paul  to  change,  Peter  will  know  what  Paul  has  and 
will  know  that  he  himself  now  has  a  seven ;  so  he  remains  content 
if  Paul  has  a  seven,  or  a  lower  card,  and  takes  another  card  if  Paul 
has  an  eight  or  a  higher  card.  Thus  Paul's  chance  arises  from  the 
hypotheses  that  Peter  originally  had  Queen,  Knave,  ten,  nine,  or 
eight     Take  one  of  these  cases,  for  example,  that  of  the  ten.     The 

chance  that  Peter  had  a  ten  is  — - ;  then  Paul  takes  it,  and  Peter 


lOS  MONTMORT. 

gets  the  seven.  There  are  50  cards  left  and  Peter  takes  one  of 
these  instead  of  his  seven ;  39  cards  out  of  the  50  are  favour- 
able to  Paul,  namely  3  sevens,  4<  Kings,  4  nines,  4i  eights,  4  sixes, 
...  4  aces. 

Proceeding  in  this  way  we  find  for  Paul's  chance 

4    47  +  43  +  39  +  35  +  31     ,,    ,  .      780 

that  IS 


51"  50  '  51.50' 

In  this  case  Paul's  chance  can  be  estimated  without  speculating 
upon  the  conduct  of  Peter,  because  there  can  be  no  doubt  as  to 
what  that  conduct  will  be. 

II.  Paul  has  a  seven;  required  his  chance  if  he  retains  the 
seven. 

The  chance  in  this  case  depends  upon  the  conduct  of  Peter. 
Now  it  appears  to  be  tacitly  allowed  by  the  disputants  that  if 
Peter  has  a  nine  or  a  higher  card  he  will  retain  it,  and  if  he  has  a 
seve7i  or  a  lower  card  he  will  take  another  instead.  The  dispute 
turns  on  what  he  will  do  if  he  has  an  eight. 

(1)     Suppose  that  Peter's  rule  is  to  retain  an  eight 

Paul's  chance  arises  from  the  hypotheses  that  Peter  has  a  seven, 

six,  five,  four,  three,   two,  or  ace,  for  which  he  proceeds  to  take 

another  card. 

We  shall  find  now,  by  the  same  method  as  before,  that  Paul's 

chance  is 

3^  24  ^  27  j^  27  _£  27   4  27  ^  27  ^  27 
51  *  50  "^  51  '  50  "^  51  *  50  "^  51  •  50  "^  51  •  50  "^  51  '  50  "^  51  •  50' 

that  is 


51.50* 


(2)     Suppose  that  Peter's  rule  is  to  change  an  eight 

4     24 
We  have  then  to  add  -pr  •  ^t:  to  the  preceding  result ;  and  thus 

51    oU 

we  obtain  for  Paul's  chance    - 


51.50' 


780 
Thus  we  find  that  in  Case  I.  Paul's  chance  is  ,  and  that 

51  .  50 

in  Case  II.  it  is  either  -,-  ^  or  .^  —.7: .     If  it  be  an  even  chance 

51 .50         51 . oU 


MOXTMOET.  109 

1  /  *720  SIP)    ^ 

■which  rule  Peter  adopts  we  should  take  ^  f --^ — p^  +  --.-^j  >  that 

is,  1^ — ^t;  as  Paul's  chance  in  Case  11.     Thus  in  Case  II.  Paul's 
51 .  oO 

chance  is  less  than  in  Case  I. ;  and  therefore  he  should  adopt  the 
rule  of  changing  when  he  has  a  seven.  This  is  one  of  the  argu- 
ments on  which  Nicolas  Bernoulli  relies. 

On  the  other  hand  his  opponents,  in  effect,  deny  the  correctness 
of  estimating  it  as  an  even  chance  that  Peter  will  adopt  either 
of  the  two  rules  which  have  been  stated. 

We  have  now  to  estimate  the  following  chance.  Peter  has  an 
eight  and  Paul  has  not  compelled  him  to  change  ;  what  is  Peter's 
chance  ?     Peter  must  argue  thus  : 

I.  Suppose  Paul's  rule  is  to  change  a  seven;  then  he  now 
has  an  eight  or  a  higher  card.  That  is,  he  must  have  one  out  of  a 
certain  23  cards. 

(1)  If  I  retain  my  eight  my  chance  of  beating  him  arises  only 
from  the  hypothesis  that  his  card  is  one  of  the  3  eights;  that  is,  my 

chance  is  ^ . 

(2)  If  I  change  my  eight  my  chance  arises  from  the  five  h}^o- 
theses  that  Paul  has  Queen,  Knave,  ten,  nine,  or  eight;  so  that  my 
chance  is 

23  ■  50  "^  23  ■  50  "^  23  ■  50  "^  23  '  50  "^  23  '  50 ' 

210 


that  is 


23 .  50 


II.     Suppose  Paul's  rule  is  to  retain  a  seven.     Then,  as  before, 

7 

(1)  If  I  retain  my  eight  my  chance  is  ^ . 

(2)  If  I  change  my  eight  my  chance  is 


4   3   4   7   4  11   4  15   3  22   4  26 

314 


27  '  50  "^  27  *  50  "^  27  ■  50  "^  27  '  50  "^  27  '  50  "^  27  ■  50 ' 


that  is 

,  27 . 50 


1  I  0  MONTMORT. 

190.  These  numerical  results  were  accepted  by  the  disjDutants. 
We  may  sum  them  up  thus.  The  question  is  whether  Paul  should 
retain  a  certain  card,  and  whether  Peter  should  retain  a  certain 
card.  If  Paul  knows  his  adversary's  rule,  he  should  adopt  the  con- 
trary, namely  retaining  when  his  adversary  changes,  and  changing 
when  his  adversary  retains.  If  Peter  knows  his  adversary's  rule  he 
should  adopt  the  same,  namely,  retaining  when  his  adversary  re- 
tains and  changing  when  his  adversary  changes. 

Now  Nicolas  Bernoulli  asserted  that  Paul  should  change,  and 
therefore  of  course  that  Peter  should.  The  objection  to  this  is 
briefly  put  thus  by  Montmort,  page  405, 

En  un  mot,  Monsieur,  si  je  SQai  que  vous  etes  le  conseil  de  Pierre, 
il  est  evident  que  je  dois  moi  Paul  me  tenir  au  sept ;  et  de  meme 
si  je  suis  Pierre,  et  qui  je  SQache  que  vous  etes  le  conseil  de  Paul, 
je  dois  changer  au  liuit,  auquel  cas  vous  aures  donne  un  mauvais  con- 
seil a  Paul. 

The  reader  will  be  reminded  of  the  old  puzzle  respecting  the 
veracity  of  the  Cretans,  since  Epimenides  the  Cretan  said  they 
were  liars. 

The  opponents  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli  at  first  contended  that  it 
was  indifferent  for  Paul  to  retain  a  seven  or  to  change  it,  and  also 
for  Peter  to  retain  an  eight  or  to  change  it ;  and  in  this  Montmort 
considered  they  were  wrong.  But  in  conversation  they  explained 
themselves  to  assert  that  no  absolute  rule  could  be  laid  down  for 
the  players,  and  in  this  Montmort  considered  that  they  were  right ; 
see  his  page  403. 

The  problem  is  considered  by  Trembley  in  the  Memoires  de 
V Acad.... Berlin,  for  1802. 

191.  The  fourth  problem  which  Montmort  proposed  for  solu^ 
tion  is  sur  le  Jen  des  Tas.     The  game  is  thus  described,  page  281, 

Pour  comprendre  de  quoi  il  s'agit,  il  faut  s9avoir  qu'apres  les  reprises 
d'hombre  un  des  Joueurs  s'amuse  sou  vent  a  partager  le  jeu  en  dix  tas 
composes  chacun  de  quatre  cartes  couvertes,  et  qu'ensuite  retournant  la 
premiere  de  chaque  tas,  il  ote  et  met  a  part  deux  ^  deux  toutes  celles 
qui  se  trouvent  semblables,  par  exemple,  deux  Pois,  deux  valets,  deux 
six,  &c.  alors  il  retourne  les  cartes  qui  suivent  immediatement  celles 
qui  viennent  de  lui  donner  des  doublets,  et  il  continue  d'oter  et  de 
mettre  a  part  celles  qui  viennent  par  doublet  jusqu'a  ce  qu'il  en  soit 


MONTMORT.  Ill 

venu  a  la  derniere  de  chaque  tas,  apres  les  avoir  enleve  toutes  deux  a 
deux,  auquel  cas  seulement  il  a  gagne. 

The  game  is  not  entirely  a  game  of  pure  chance,  because  the 
l^layer  may  often  have  a  choice  of  various  methods  of  pjairing  and 
removing  cards.  In  the  description  of  the  game  forty  cards  are 
supposed  to  be  used,  but  Montmort  proposes  the  problem  for  solu- 
tion generally  without  limiting  the  cards  to  forty.  He  requires 
the  chance  the  player  has  of  winning  and  also  the  most  ad- 
vantageous method  of  i^roceeding.  He  says  the  game  was  rarely 
played  for  money,  but  intimates  that  it  was  in  use  aniong  ladies. 

192.  On  his  page  821  Montmort  gives,  without  demonstration, 
the  result  in  a  particular  case  of  this  problem,  namely  when  the 
cards  consist  of  ?2  pairs,  the  two  cards  in  each  pair  being  numbered 
alike  ;  the  cards  are  supposed  placed  at  random  in  n  lots,  each  of 
two  cards.     He  says  that  the  chance  the  player  has  of  winning  is 

92  —  1 

^ — -.     On  page  334^  Nicolas  Bernoulli  says  that  this  formula  is 

correct,  but  he  wishes  to  know  how  it  was  found,  because  he  him- 
self can  only  find  it  by  induction,  by  jDutting  for  n  in  succession 
2,  3,  ^,o,  ...We  may  suppose  this  means  that  Nicolas  Bernoulli  veri- 
fied by  trial  that  the  formula  was  correct  in  certain  cases,  but  could 
not  give  a  general  demonstration.  Montmort  seems  to  have 
overlooked  Nicolas  Bernoulli's  inquiry,  for  the  problem  is  never 
mentioned  again  in  the  course  of  the  correspondence.  As  the  result 
is  remarkable  for  its  simplicity,  and  as  Nicolas  Bernoulli  found  the 
problem  difficult,  it  may  be  interesting  to  give  a  solution.  It  will 
be  observed  that  in  this  case  the  game  is  one  of  pure  chance,  as  the 
player  never  has  any  choice  of  courses  open  to  him. 

193.  The  solution  of  the  problem  depends  on  our  observing 
the  state  of  the  cards  at  the  epoch  at  which  the  player  loses,  that 
is  at  the  epoch  at  which  he  can  make  no  more  pairs  among  the 
cards  exj^osed  to  view ;  the  player  may  be  thus  arrested  at  the 
very  beginning  of  the  game,  or  after  he  has  already  taken  som^j 
steps :  at  this  epoch  the  player  is  left  icitk  some  number  of  lots, 
which  are  all  unbroken,  and  the  cards  exposed  to  vieiu  present  no 
pairs.     This  will  be  obvious  on  reflection. 


1 1  2  MONTMORT. 

We  must  now  determine  (1)  the  whole  number  of  possible 
cases,  and  (2)  the  whole  number  of  cases  in  which  the  player  is 
arrested  at  the  very  beginning. 

(1)  We  may  suppose  that  2n  cards  are  to  be  put  in  2n 
places,  and  thus  [  27i  will  be  the  whole  number  of  possible  cases. 

(2)  Here  we  may  find  the  number  of  cases  by  supposing  that 
the  n  upper  places  are  first  filled  and  then  the  n  lower  places. 
We  may  put  m  the  first  place  any  card  oat  of  the  2/2,  then  in  the 
second  place  any  card  of  the  2n  —  2  which  remain  by  rejecting  the 
companion  card  to  that  we  put  in  the  first  place,  then  in  the  third 
place  any  card  of  the  2n  —  4<  which  remain  by  rejecting  the  two 
companion  cards,  and  so  on.  Thus  the  n  upper  places  can  be 
filled  in  2" [n  ways.  Then  the  n  lower  places  can  be  filled  in  [n 
ways.  Hence  we  get  2*"  1^2  [ji  cases  in  which  the  player  is  arrested 
at  the  very  beginning. 

We  may  divide  each  of  these  expressions  by  \n  if  we  please 

to  disregard  the  different  order  in  which  the  n  lots  may  be  sup- 

\2n 
posed  to  be  arranged.      Thus  the  results  become   M^  and  2"  [n 

respectively ;  we  shall  use  these  forms. 

Let  u^  denote  the  whole  number  of  unfavourable  cases,  and  let 
/,.  denote  the  whole  number  of  favourable  cases  when  the  cards 
consist  of  r  pairs.     Then 

u^=^r[n  +  t  -—^ £  \n-r  2""'', 


the  summation  extending  from  r  =  2  to  r  =  w  —  1,  both  inclusive. 

For,  as  we  have  stated,  the  player  loses  by  being  left  with  some 
number  of  lots,  all  unbroken,  in  which  the  exposed  cards  contain 
no  pairs.     Suppose  he  is  left  with  n  —  r  lots,  so  that  he  has  got  rid 

\  71 

of  r  lots  of  the  original  n  lots.     The  factor != g-ives  the  num- 

\r  n  —  r 

ber  of  ways  in  which  r  pairs  can  be  selected  from  n  pairs ;  the 
factor  fi  gives  the  number  of  ways  in  which  these  pairs  can  be  so 
arranged  as  to  enable  the  player  to  get  rid  of  them  ;  the  fiictor 
\n  —  r  2""'"  gives  the  number  of  ways  in  which  the  remaining  n  —  r 

pairs  can  be  distributed  into  n  —  r  lots  without  a  single  pair  occur- 
ring among  the  exposed  cards. 


MONTMORT.  113 

It  is  to  be  observed  that  the  case  in  which  r  =  l  does  not 
occur,  from  the  nature  of  the  game  ;  for  the  player,  if  not  arrested 
at  the  very  beginning,  will  certainly  be  able  to  remove  tivo  pairs. 
We  may  how^ever  if  we  please  consider  the  summation  to  extend 
from  r  =  lio  r  =  n-l,  since/.  =  0  when  r  =  1. 

We  have  then 


u„=.T\n[l  +  2J^. 


The  summation  for  w„_,  extends  to  one  term  less ;  thus  we 
shall  find  that 

But  «„.,  +/„_,  = 


71-1 


therefore 


2/2  I  2;i  -  2 


n  —  l 


\1n  2\2?i-2  I  2/1      ,j_i 

Hence    /„  =  i=  -  z/„  =-==-- ;   and /„ -^ 


[w         "        1 71 -2    '        ^"  •     |_^      2/4 -l' 
,    This  is  Montmort's  result. 

19^.  We  noAv  arrive  at  what  Montmort  calls  the  fifth  part 
of  his  work,  which  occupies  pages  288 — 41-i.  It  consists  of  the 
coiTcspondence  between  Montmort  and  Nicolas  Bernoulli,  together 
with  one  letter  from  John  Bernoulli  to  Montmort  and  a  reply 
from  Montmort.  The  whole  of  this  part  is  new  in  the  second 
edition. 

John  Bernoulli,  the  friend  of  Leibnitz  and  the  master  of  Euler, 
was  the  third  brother  in  the  family  of  brothers  of  whom  James 
Bernoulli  was  the  eldest.  John  was  born  in  1667,  and  died  in 
IT-iS.  The  second  brother  of  the  family  was  named  Nicolas ;  his 
son  of  the  same  name,  the  friend  and  corres^oondent  of  Montmort, 
was  born  in   16S7,  and  died  in  1759. 

195.  Some  of  the  letters  relate  to  Montmort's  first  edition, 
and  it  is  necessary  to  have  access  to  this  edition  to  study  the 
letters  with  advantage ;  because  although  Montmort  gives  re- 
ferences to  the  corresponding  passages  in  the  second  edition,  yet 

8 


114?  MONTMORT. 

as  these  passages  have  been  modified  or  corrected  in  accordance 
with  the  criticisms  contained  in  the  letters,  it  is  not  always  ob- 
vious what  the  original  reading  was. 

196.  The  first  letter  is  from  John  Bernoulli ;  it  occupies 
pages  283 — 298  ;  the  letter  is  also  reprinted  in  the  collected 
edition  of  John  Bernoulli's  works,  in  four  volumes,  Lausanne  and 
Geneva,  1742 ;  see  Vol.  I.  page  453. 

John  Bernoulli  gives  a  series  of  remarks  on  Montmort's  first 
edition,  correcting  some  errors  and  suggesting  some  improvements. 
He  shews  that  Montmort  did  not  present  his  discussion  relating 
to  Pharaon  in  the  simplest  form ;  Montmort  however  did  not 
modify  this  part  of  his  work.  John  Bernoulli  gave  a  general 
formula  for  the  advantage  of  the  Banker,  and  this  Montmort  did 
adopt,  as  we  have  seen  in  Art.  155. 

197.  John  Bernoulli  points  out  a  curious  mistake  made 
by  Montmort  twice  in  his  first  edition ;  see  his  pages  288,  296. 
Montmort  had  considered  it  practically  impossible  to  find  the 
numerical  value  of  a  certain  number  of  terms  of  a  geometrical 
progression ;  it  would  seem  that  he  had  forgotten  or  never  known 
the  common  Algebraical  formula  which  gives  the  sum.  The 
passages  cited  by  John  Bernoulli  are  from  pages  35  and  181  of 
the  first  edition ;  but  in  the  only  copy  which  I  have  seen  of  the 
first  edition  the  text  does  not  correspond  with  John  Bernoulli's 
quotations  :  it  appears  however  that  in  each  place  the  original  page 
has  been  cancelled  and  replaced  by  another  in  order  to  correct 
the  mistake. 

After  noticing  the  mistake,  John  Bernoulli  proceeds  thus  in 
his  letter : 

...mais  pour  le  reste,  vous  faites  bien  d'employer  les  logarithm es, 
je  m'en  suis  servi  utilement  dans  une  parcille  occasion  il  y  a  bien 
douze  ans,  ou  il  s'agissoit  de  determiner  combien  il  restoit  de  vin  et 
d'eau  mele  ensemble  dans  un  tonneau,  lequel  etant  an  commencement 
tout  plein  de  vin,  on  en  tireroit  tons  les  jours  pendant  une  amice 
une  certaine  mesure,  en  le  remplissant  incontinent  apres  cliaque  ex- 
traction avec  de  I'eau  pure.  Vous  trouveres  la  solution  de  cette  ques- 
tion qui  est  asses  curieuse  dans  ma  dissertation  De  Nutritlone,  que  Mr 
Varignon  vous  pourra  communiquer.      Jc  fis  cette  question  pour  faire 


MONTMORT.  115 

comprendre  comment  on  pent  determiner  la  quantite  de  vieille  ma- 
tiere  qui  reste  dans  nos  corps  melee  avec  de  la  nouvelle  qui  nous 
vient  tous  les  jours  par  la  nourriture,  pour  reparer  la  perte  que  nos 
corps  font  insensiblement  par  la  transpiration  continuelle. 

The  dissertation  De  Nutritione  will  be  found  in  the  collected 
edition  of  John  Bernoulli's  works  ;  see  Vol.  I.  page  275. 

198.  John  Bernoulli  passes  on  to  a  remark  on  Montmort's 
discussion  of  the  game  of  Treize.  The  remark  enunciates  the 
following  theorem. 

Let  <^(.)  =  l--^+^-^+...+-^ 

and  let 


n 


t(«)=^(«)  +  J^("-l)  +  U(n-2)+...+  ^^<^(1); 


111  1 


then  shall  i/r  {n)  =  --[-+_++. ..+_. 

^     [^    [I    [±  \JL 

We  may  prove  this  by  induction.     For  we  may  write  yjr  (n)  in 
the  following  form, 

T      fl  1  1  1  1  1 


^11 

2  ]  ^  '  1  '  12  '  [3_ 


1  r,    1     1     1  1    1 

-o^  l  +  T  +  n5  +  rT.  + +  ^^3^  J 


n 


Hence  we  can  shew  that 

y}r  (n  +  1)  =  i/r  {n)  + 


;i  +  1  * 


199.  John  Bernoulli  next  adverts  to  the  solutions  which 
Montmort  had  given  of  the  five  problems  proposed  by  Huygens ; 
see  Art.  35. 

According  to  John  Bernoulli's  opinion,  Montmort  had  not 
understood  the  second  and  third  problems  in  the  sense  which 
Huygens   had   intended ;    in   the    fifth   problem   Montmort   had 

8-^2 


116  MONTMORT. 

changed  the  enunciation  into  another  quite  different,  and  yet  had 
really  solved  the  problem  according  to  Huygens's  enunciation.  By 
the  corrections  which  he  made  in  his  second  edition,  Montmort 
shewed  that  he  admitted  the  justice  of  the  objections  urged  against 
his  solutions  of  the  second  and  fifth  problems;  in  the  case  of 
the  third  problem  he  retained  his  original  opinion;  see  his 
pages  292,  805. 

John  Bernoulli  next  notices  the  solution  of  the  Problem  of 
Points,  and  gives  a  general  formula,  to  which  we  have  referred  in 
Art.  173.  Then  he  adverts  to  a  problem  which  Montmort  had 
not  fully  considered;  see  Art.  185. 

200.  John  Bernoulli  gives  high  praise  to  Montmort's  work, 
but  urges  him  to  extend  and  enrich  it.  He  refers  to  the  four 
problems  which  Montmort  had  proposed  for  investigation ;  the 
first  he  considers  too  long  to  be  finished  in  human  life,  and  the 
fourth  he  cannot  understand :  the  other  two  he  thinks  might  be 
solved  by  great  labour.  This  opinion  seems  singularly  incorrect. 
The  first  problem  is  the  easiest  of  all,  and  has  been  solved  without 
difficulty;  see  Article  161  :  perhaps  however  John  Bernoulli  took 
it  in  some  more  general  sense;  see  Montmort's  page  308.  The 
fourth  problem  is  quite  intelligible,  and  a  particular  case  of  it  is 
simple ;  see  Art.  193.  The  third  and  fourth  problems  seem  to  be 
far  more  intractable. 

201.  A  letter  to  Montmort  from  Nicolas  Bernoulli  occupies 
pages  299 — 303.  This  letter  contains  corrections  of  two  mistakes 
which  occurred  in  Montmort's  first  edition.  It  gives  without  de- 
monstration a  formula  for  the  advantage  of  the  Banker  at  Pharaon, 
and  also  a  formula  for  the  advantage  of  the  Banker  at  Bassette  ; 
Montmort  quoted  the  former  in  the  text  of  his  second  edition  ; 
see  Art.  157.  Nicolas  Bernoulli  gives  a  good  investigation  of  the 
formulae  which  occur  in  analysing  the  game  of  Treize  ;  see  Art.  161. 
He  also  discusses  briefly  a  game  of  chance  which  we  will  now 
explain. 

202.  Suppose  that  a  set  of  players  A,  B,  C,  D, ...  undertake 
to  play  a  set  of  I  games  with  cards.  A  is  at  first  the  dealer,  there 
are  m  chances  out  of  on  +  n  that  he  retains  the  deal  at  the  next 
game,  and  n  chances  out  of  m  +  7i  that  he  loses  it ;  if  he  loses  the 


MONTMORT.  117 

deal  the  player  on  Lis  right  hand  takes  it ;  and  so  on  in  order. 
B  is  on  the  left  of  A,  C  is  on  the  left  of  B,  and  so  on.  Let  the 
advantages  of  the  players  when  A  deals  .be  a,  h,  c,  d,  ...  respec- 
tively; these  advantages  are  supposed  to  depend  entirely  on 
the  situation  of  the  players,  the  game  being  a  game  of  pure 
chance. 

Let  the  chances  of  A,  B,  C,  D, ...  bo  denoted  by  z,  y,  x,  u,  ... ; 
and  let  s  =  7n  +  7l 

Then  Nicolas  Bernoulli  gives  the  following  values  : 

z  =  a  +  —^  + ~, + -, +..., 

,       7nh  +  nc     m^h  4-  2mnc-\-n^d     m%-^Snfnc  +  2mn^d+  n^e 
2/  =  i  +  -^-  + p + p +..., 

.  mc  +  7id     7n'^G-\-27n7id-{-7i^e     7ifc-h2m^7id+Sm7i^e  +  72^f 

^  =  0  +  ^— + 7 +  — ? -  +  ■■■' 


_  ,     md  +  7ie     m^d-\-2miie+ri^f     7n^d-\-Sm^ne  +  Sm7}^f+7i'g 
and  so  on. 


Each  of  these  series  is  to  continue  for  I  terms.  If  there  are 
not  so  many  as  I  players,  the  letters  in  the  set  a,  h,  c,  d,  e,f,(/,... 
will  recur.  For  example,  if  there  are  only  four  players,  then 
e  =  a,  f=h,  g  =  c,.... 

It  is  easy  to  see  the  meaning  of  the  separate  terms.     Take,  for 
example,  the  value  of  z.     A  deals  ;  the  advantage  directly  arising 
from  this  is  a.   Then  there  are  m  chances  out  of  5  that  A  will  hav 
the  second  deal,  and  7i  chances  out  of  s  that  the  deal  will  pass  o. 
to  the  next  player,  and  thus  put  A  in  the  position  originally  hek 

by  B.     Hence  we  have  the  term .     Again,  for  the   third 

deal ;  there  are  (rti  +  7iy,  that  is,  s^  possible  cases  ;  out  of  these 

there  are  711^  cases  in  which  A  will  have  the  third  deal,  2mn  cases 

in  which  the  player  on  the  right  of  A  will  have  it,  and  n"^  cases  in 

which   the   player   next   on   the  right  w^ill  have   it.     Hence   we 

,  ,1      ,  iii^a -\- Imnh -\- 7i^c        .     , 

nave  the  term z .     And  so  on. 


118 


MONTMOET. 


Nicolas  Bernoulli  then  gives  another  form  for  these  expressions  ; 
we  will  exhibit  that  for  z  from  which  the  others  can  be  deduced. 


Let 


^^i,    ,=  K     ,=  !i.     Then 
^      n  \sj  m 


z  =  aq(l-r)-\-hq\l-r{l-\-tl]\-\-C(i\l-r 


r      _    fia-r)~\] 


-{■dq  \l  —  r 


-^  ^  ^^  ^  tH{i-i)  ^  fi{i-i)(i-2y 


1.2 


1.2.3 


I  •  •  •  J 


this  series  is  to  be  continued  for  I  terms. 

The  way  in  which  this  transformation  is  effected  is  the  follow- 
ing :  suppose  for  example  we  pick  out  the  coefficient  of  c  in  the 
value  of  z,  we  shall  find  it  to  be 

1  .Zs    [  s  s  s'^  ) 

where  the  series  in  brackets  is  to  consist  of  Z  —  2  terms. 
We  have  then  to  shew  that  this  expression  is  equal  to 


«{'-'h"*'^']}- 


We  will  take  the  general  theorem  of  which  this  is  a  particular 
case.     Let 


where 


Let 


P.= 


p  +  X-1 


u 


1  +  -  +  -T  + 


then  S=T—  -y-^ . 
[Xdmr' 


Now 


-       fmr 


u  — 


1- 


la 


say; 


MOXTMORT.  119 

1.2  s^         (l-At/"' 


1.2.3  6'^  (l-/x) 


\-2 


-^^!i   rli  I  til  ^^^-^   tn{i-i)(i-2)      ■ 

-    ,,,U     »     i  +  ^^+      ^^2      +         1.2.3         "^••• 


71^-^^ 


where  the  series  between  square  brackets  is  to  extend  to  X  + 1 
terms. 

We  may  observe  that  by  the  nature  of  the  problem  we  have 

a  +  Z>  +  c  +  ...=0,  and  also  z+y  +  x+...  =  0. 

The  problem  simplifies  very  much  if  we  may  regard  I  as  infinite 
or  very  great.  For  then  let  z  denote  the  advantage  of  -4  ;  if  ^  ob- 
tains the  next  deal  we  may  consider  that  his  advantage  is  still  z  ;  if 
A  loses  the  next  deal  his  advantage  is  the   same  as  that  of  B 

originally.     Thus 

mz  +  n2/ 

s 

MultijDly  by  s  and  transpose  ;  therefore 

z  =  7/-{-  aq. 
Similarly  we  have 

y  =  x  +  hq,    x  =  ii  +  cq,    

Hence  we  shall  obtain 

^  =  2L(^-l)  +  &(p-2)  +  c(i?-3)  +  ...j, 

where  p  denotes  the  number  of  players  ;  and  the  values  of  y,  ^, . . . 
may  be  obtained  by  symmetrical  changes  in  the  letters. 
We  may  also  express  the  result  thus, 


z 


=  _£|a+2^>+3c+...|. 


120  MONTMORT. 

203.  The  next  letter  is  from  Montmort  to  John  Bernoulli ;  it 
occupies  pages  803 — 307.  Montmort  makes  brief  observations  on 
the  points  to  which  John  Bernouilli  had  drawn  his  attention ;  he 
suggests  a  problem  on  the  Duration  of  Play  for  the  consideration 
of  Nicolas  Bernoulli. 

204.  The  next  letter  is  from  Nicolas  Bernoulli  to  Montmort ; 
it  occupies  pages  808 — 814. 

Nicolas  Bernoulli  first  speaks  of  the  game  of  Treize,  and  gives 
a  general  formula  for  it ;  but  by  accident  he  gave  the  formula  in- 
correctly, and  afterwards  corrected  it  w^hen  Montmort  drew  his 
attention  to  it ;  see  Montmort's  pages  815,  328. 

We  will  here  investigate  the  formula  after  the  manner  given  by 
Nicolas  BernoulH  for  the  simple  case  already  considered  in  Art.  161. 

Suppose  there  are  n  cards  divided  into  p  sets.     Denote  the 
cards  of  a  set  by  a,h,c,...  in  order. 
The  whole  number  of  cases  is  \n. 
The  number  of  ways  in  which  a  can  stand  first  is  p  \n  —  \. 

The  number  of  ways  in  which  h  can  stand  second  without  a 
standing  first  is  p  \n  —  l  —  p\  n 


The  number  of  ways  in  which  c  can  stand  third  without  a 
standing  first  or  h  second  is  p  \n  —  \  —  2p^  |^  —  2  +  p^  |  n  —  3. 
And  so  on. 

Hence  the  chance  of  winning  by  the  first  card  is  -  ;  the  chance 


n 


of  winning:  by  the  second  card  is -, ^    ,.  ;  the  chance  of  Avin- 

°    -^  n     7i{n—  1) 

ning  by  the  third  card  is  — ,  ^  .,.  H 7 =^-7 -^ ;  and  so  on. 

°    ''  n     n{n—l)      n{n—  1)  [ii  —  z) 

Hence  the  chance  of  winning  by  one  or  other  of  the  first  m 
cards  is 

mjj     m  (m  —  1)       p^  m  (m  —  1)  {m  —  2)  p^ 

"^"'       O       n  {n  -  1)  "^  1.2.3  7i  (n  -  1)  (w -2)  ""  *'* 

And    the    entire    chance    of    winning   is    found    by   putting 

m  =  - ,  so  that  it  is 
P 


MONTMORT.  121 

1  n  —J)  {n  —p)  (n  —  2p) 

i  "  1 .  2  (7i  -  1)  "^  1 .  2 .  3  (?i  -  1)  (n  -  2) 

(n  —p)  (n  —  2p)  (n  —  8/;) 
""1.2. 3. 4(7-^-1)  (w-2)  (/i^Ts)  +••• 

205.  Nicolas  Bernoulli  then  passes  on  to  another  game  in 
which  he  objects  to  Montmort's  conclusion.  Montmort  had  found 
a  certain  advantage  for  the  first  player,  on  the  assumption  that  the 
game  was  to  conclude  at  a  certain  stage ;  Nicolas  Bernoulli  thought 
that  at  this  stage  the  game  ought  not  to  terminate,  but  that  the 
players  should  change  their  positions.  He  says  that  the  advantage 
for  the  first  player  should  be  only  half  what  Montmort  stated. 
The  point  is  of  little  interest,  as  it  does  not  belong  to  the  theory  of 
chances  but  to  the  conventions  of  the  players  ;  Montmort,  however, 
did  not  admit  the  justice  of  the  remarks  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli ;  see 
Montmort's  pages  309,  317,  327. 

206.  Nicolas  Bernoulli  then  considers  the  problem  on  the 
Duration  of  Play  which  had  been  suggested  for  him  by  Mont- 
mort. Nicolas  Bernoulli  here  gives  the  formulaa  to  which  we  have 
already  alluded  in  Art.  ISO;  but  the  meaning  of  the  formuloB  was 
very  obscure,  as  Montmort  stated  in  his  reply.  Nicolas  Bernoulli 
gives  the  result  which  expresses  the  chances  of  each  player  when 
the  number  of  games  is  unlimited ;  he  says  this  may  be  deduced 
from  the  general  formulae,  and  that  he  had  also  obtained  it  pre- 
viously by  another  method.     See  Art.  107. 

207.  Nicolas  Bernoulli  then  makes  some  remarks  on  the 
summation  of  series.  He  exemplifies  the  method  which  is  now 
common  in  elementary  works  on  Algebra.  Sujipose  we  require 
the  sum  of  the  squares  of  the  first  n  triangular  numbers,  that  is,  the 

sum  of  n  terms  of  the  series  of  which  the  r^^  term  is  \---^ — —^ 

Assume  that  the  sum  is  equal  to 

an^  +  hn^  +  cn^  +  dn^  +  en  + /*; 

and  then  determine  a,  h,  c,  d,  e,  f  by  changing  n  into  n-\-\  in 
the  assumed  identity,  subtracting,  and  equating  coefficients.  This 
method   is   ascribed   by   Nicolas    Bernoulli    to   his    uncle   John, 


122  MONTMOET. 

Nicolas   Bernoulli   also    indicates   another  method ;    he   resolves 
^(f  +  l)finto 

r  (r+l)(r  +  2)  (r  +  3)  _     r  (r  +  1)  (r+2)      7-  (r  +  1) 
1.2.3.4  1.2.3         "^     1.2     ' 

and  thus  finds  that  the  required  sum  is 

??0^4-l)  02+2)  (M+3)(n  +  4)  __     ^  (72  +  1)  (w  +  2)  (?z  +  3) 
1.2.3.4.5  1.2.3.4 

w  (^  4- 1)  (w  +  2) 


4- 


1.2.3 


208.  It  seems  probable  that  a  letter  from  Montmort  to 
Nicolas  Bernoulli,  which  has  not  been  preserved,  preceded  this 
letter  from  Nicolas  Bernoulli.  For  Nicolas  Bernoulli  refers  to  the 
problem  about  a  lottery,  as  if  Montmort  had  drawn  his  attention 
to  it ;  see  Art.  180  :  and  he  intimates  that  Montmort  had  offered 
to  undertake  the  printing  of  James  Bernoulli's  unpublished  Ars 
Conjectandi.  Neither  of  these  points  had  been  mentioned  in 
Montmort's  preceding  letters  as  we  have  them  in  the  book. 

209.  The  next  letter  is  from  Montmort  to  Nicolas  Bernoulli ; 
it  occupies  pages  315 — 323.  The  most  interesting  matter  in  this 
letter  is  the  introduction  for  the  first  time  of  a  problem  which  has 
since  been  much  discussed.  The  problem  was  proposed  to  Mont- 
mort, and  also  solved,  by  an  English  gentleman  named  Waldegrave ; 
see  Montmort's  pages  318  and  328.  In  the  problem  as  originally 
proposed  only  three  players  are  considered,  but  we  will  enunciate 
it  more  generally.  Suppose  there  are  n-{-l  players  ;  two  of  them 
play  a  game ;  the  loser  deposits  a  shilling,  and  the  winner  then 
plays  with  the  third  player ;  the  loser  deposits  a  shilling,  and 
the  winner  then  plays  with  the  fourth  player ;  and  so  on.  The 
player  who  lost  the  first  game  does  not  enter  again  until  after  the 
{n  -\-iy^  player  has  had  his  turn.  The  process  continues  until 
one  player  has  beaten  in  continued  succession  all  the  other  players, 
and  then  he  receives  all  the  money  which  has  been  deposited. 
It  is  required  to  determine  the  expectation  of  each  of  the  players, 
and  also  the  chance  that  the  money  will  be  won  when,  or  before, 
a  certain  number  of  games  has  been  played.     The  game  is  sup- 


MONTMORT.  123 

posed  a  game  of  pure  chance,  or  wliicli  is  the  same  thing,  the 
jjlayers  are  all  supposed  of  equal  skill. 

Montmort  himself  in  the  case  of  three  players  states  all  the 
required  results,  but  does  not  give  demonstrations.  In  the  case 
of  four  players  he  states  the  numerical  probability  that  the  money 
■will  be  won  in  any  assigned  number  of  games  between  3  and  13 
inclusive,  but  he  says  that  the  law  of  the  numbers  which  he 
assigns  is  not  easy  to  perceive.  He  attempted  to  proceed  further 
with  the  j^roblem,  and  to  determine  the  advantage  of  each  player 
when  there  are  four  players,  and  also  to  determine  the  pro- 
bability of  the  money  being  won  in  an  assigned  number  of  games 
when  there  are  five  or  six  players.  He  says  however,  page  320, 
mais  cela  m'a  paru  trop  difficile,  ou  pltitot  j'ai  manque  de  courage, 
car  je  serois  stir  d'en  venir  a  bout. 

210.  There  are  references  to  this  problem  several  times  in 
the  correspondence  of  Montmort  and  Nicolas  Bernoulli ;  see  Mont- 
mort's  pages  328,  34^5,  350,  3G6,  875,  380,  400.  Nicolas  Bernoulli 
succeeded  in  solving  the  problem  generally  for  any  number  of 
players ;  his  solution  is  given  in  Montmort's  pages  381 — 387,  and 
is  perhaps  the  most  striking  investigation  in  the  work.  The 
following  remarks  may  be  of  service  to  a  student  of  this  solution. 

(1)  On  page  386  Nicolas  Bernoulli  ought  to  have  stated 
how  many  terms  should  be  taken  of  the  two  series  which  he  gives, 
namely,  a  number  expressed  by  the  greatest  integer  contained 

in — .     On  page  330  where  he  does  advert  to  this  point 

he  puts  by  mistake  —  instead  of . 

(2)  The  expressions  given  for  a,  h,  c, ...   on   j^age  386  are 

2 

correct,  excej)t  that  given  for  a ;  the  value  of  «  is  ^ ,  and  not 

■^ ,  as  the  language  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli  seems  to  imply. 

(3)  The  chief  results  obtained  by  Nicolas  Bernoulli  are  stated 
at  the  top  of  page  329  ;  these  results  agree  with  tliose  afterwards 
given  by  Laplace. 


124  MONTMORT. 

211.  Althougli  the  earliest  iiotice  of  the  problem  occurs  in 
the  letter  of  Montmort's  which  we  are  now  examining,  yet  the 
earliest  piiblicatioyi  of  it  is  due  to  De  Moivre ;  it  is  Problem  XV. 
of  the  De  Mensura  Sortis.  We  shall  however  speak  of  it  as 
Waldegraves  Problem,  from  the  person  whose  name  we  have  found 
first  associated  with  it. 

The  problem  is  discussed  by  Laplace,  Theorie . . .  des  Froh. 
page  238,  and  we  shall  therefore  have  to  recur  to  it. 

212.  Montmort  refers  on  page  320  to  a  book  entitled  Traite 
dii  Jeu,  which  he  says  he  had  lately  received  from  Paris.  He  says 
it  is  un  Livre  de  morale.  He  praises  the  author,  but  considers 
him  to  be  wrong  sometimes  in  his  calculation  of  chances,  and 
gives  an  example.  Nicolas  Bernoulli  in  reply  says  that  the 
author  of  the  book  is  Mr  Barbeyrac.  Nicolas  Bernoulli  agrees 
with  Montmort  in  his  general  opinion  respecting  the  book,  but 
in  the  example  in  question  he  thinks  Barbeyrac  right  and  Mont- 
mort wrong.  The  difference  in  result  arises  from  a  difference  in 
the  way  of  understanding  the  rules  of  the  game.  Montmort 
briefly  replied ;  see  pages  332,  3-i6. 

Montmort  complains  of  a  dearth  of  mathematical  memoirs  ;  he 
says,  page  322, 

Je  suis  etonne  de  voir  les  Journeaux  de  Lei23sic  si  degarnis  de 
morceaux  de  Matliematiques :  ils  doivent  en  partie  leur  reputation  aux 
excellens  Memoires  que  Messieurs  vos  Oiicles  y  envoyoient  souveiit :  les 
Geometres  n'y  trouvent  plus  depuis  cinq  ou  six  ans  les  memes  ricliesses 
qu' autrefois,  faites-en  des  reproches  a  M.  votre  Oncle,  et  permettcs-nioi 
de  vous  en  faire  aussi,  Luceat  lux  vestra  coram  hominihus. 

213.  The  next  letter  is  from  Nicolas  Bernoulli  to  Montmort ; 
it  occupies  pages  323 — 337.  It  chiefly  relates  to  matters  which 
we  have  already  sufficiently  noticed,  namely,  the  games  of  Treize, 
Her,  and  Tas,  and  Waldcgrave's  Problem.  Nicolas  Bernoulli  ad- 
verts to  the  letter  by  his  uncle  James  on  the  game  of  Tennis, 
which  was  afterwards  published  at  the  end  of  the  Ars  Conjectandi, 
and  he  proposes  for  solution  four  of  the  problems  which  are  con- 
sidered in  the  letter  in  order  to  see  if  Montmort's  results  will 
agree  with  those  of  James  Bernoulli. 


MONTMORT.  125 

Nicolas  Bernoulli  gives  at  the  end  of  his  letter  an  example 
)f  summation  of  series.  He  proposes  to  sum  p  terms  of  the 
jeries  1,  3,  6,  10,  15,  21,  ...     He  considers  the  series 

1  +  3:c  +  6aj'  +  lOa;^  +  lox"  +  21^'  +  ... 

which  he  decomposes  into  a  set  of  series,  thus : 

1  +  2a;  +  3x'  +  ^x^  +  5;c*  +  ... 

+    a;  +  2a;'  +  3^'  +  4ic*+ ... 

+    ir'  +  2a;'  +  3^'+... 

+     33^+2^'+... 

+    0;*+... 
+  ... 
The  series  in  each  horizontal  row  is  easily  summed  to  p  terms ; 

he  expression  obtained  takes  the  form  -  when  x  =  l,  and  Nicolas 

Bernoulli  evaluates  the  indeterminate  form,  as  he  says,  ...en  me 
servant  de  la  regie  de  mon  Oncle,  que  feu  Monsieur  le  Marquis 
de  I'Hojoital  a  insere  dans  son  Analyse  des  infiniment  petits, ... 

The  investigation  is  very  inaccurately  printed. 

21 -i.  The  next  letter  is  from  Montmort  to  Nicolas  Bernoulli ; 
it  occupies  pages  337 — 317.  Besides  remarks  on  the  game  of  Her 
and  on  Waldegrave's  Problem,  it  contains  some  attempts  at  the 
problems  which  Nicolas  Bernoulli  had  proposed  out  of  his  uncle's 
letter  on  the  game  of  Tennis.  But  Montmort  found  the  problems 
difficult  to  understand,  and  asked  several  questions  as  to  their 
meaning. 

215.  Montmort  gives  on  his  page  312  the  following  equation 
as  the  result  of  one  of  the  problems, 

4m'-8m'+llM  +  6  =  3'"-'\ 

and  he  says  that  this  is  satisfied  approximately  by  m  =  of-J^ ;  but 
there  is  some  mistake,  for  the  equation  has  no  root  between 
5  and  6.     The  correct  equation  should  apparently  be 

which  has  a  root  between  51  and  5 •2. 


126  MONTMORT. 

216.  One  of  the  problems  is  the  following.  The  skill  of  ^, 
that  is  his  chance  of  success  in  a  single  trial,  is  ^,  the  skill  of  B 
is  q.  A  and  B  are  to  play  for  victory  in  two  games  out  of  three, 
each  game  being  for  two  points.  In  the  first  game  B  is  to  have 
a  point  given  to  him,  in  the  second  the  players  are  to  be  on  an 
equality,  and  in  the  third  also  B  is  to  have  a  point  given  to 
him.  Required  the  skill  of  each  player  so  that  on  the  whole 
the  chances  may  be  equal,  ^'s  chance  of  success  in  the  first 
game  or  in  the  third  game  is  p^,  and  i?'s  chance  is  ^  +  '^qp. 
u4's  chance  of  success  in  the  second  game  is  p^  +  ^p^q,  and  ^'s 
chance  is  <f  +  3^^.  Hence  ^'s  chance  of  success  in  two  games 
out  of  three  is 

/  (/  +  3/2)  +/  (2'  +  ^P)  (p'  +  3/2)  +/  (q"  +  32»  ; 
and  this  by  supposition  must  equal  ^ . 

This   agrees  with   Montmort's  result  by  putting  ,   for  ^ 

and 7    for  g,  allowinc^  for  a  mistake   which   was  afterwards 

corrected  ;  see  Montmort's  pages  34^3,  350,  352. 

217.  The  letter  closes  with  the  following  interesting  piece  of 
literary  history. 

Je  ne  sgai  si  vous  slaves  qu'on  reimprime  la  Recherche  de  la  verite. 
Le  R.  P.  Malbranche  m'a  dit  que  cet  Ouvi-age  paroitroit  au  commence- 
ment d'Avril.  II  y  aura  un  grand  nonibre  d'additions  sur  des  sujets 
tres  importans.  Yous  y  verres  entr'autres  nouveautes  une  Disserta- 
tion sur  la  cause  de  la  pesanteur,  qui  apparemment  fixera  les  doutes 
de  tant  de  Sgavans  hommes  qui  ne  sgavent  a  quoi  s'en  tenir  sur 
cette  matiere.  II  prouve  d'une  maniere  invincible  la  necessite  de  ses 
petits  tourbillons  pour  rendre  raison  de  la  cause  de  la  pesanteur,  de  la 
durete  et  fluidite  des  corps  et  des  principaux  plienomenes  toucliant  la 
lumiere  et  les  couleursj  sa  theorie  s'accorde  le  niieux  du  monde  avec 
les  belles  experiences  que  M.  Newton  a  rapporte  dans  son  beau  Traite 
Be  Natura  Lucis  et  Colorum.  Je  peux  me  glorifier  auprcs  du  Pub- 
lic que  mes  prieres  ardentes  et  reiterees  depuis  j)lusieurs  annces,  ont 
contribue  a  determiner  cet  incomparable  Philosoplie  a  ecrire  sur  cette 


MONTMORT.  127 

matiere  qiii  renfcrme  toute  la  Physique  generale.  Vous  verres  avec 
admiration  que  ce  grand  hiomme  a  porte  dans  ces  matieres  obscures 
cette  nettete  d'idces,  cette  sublimite  de  genie  et  d'invention  qui  bril- 
lent  avec  tant  d'eclat  dans  ses  Traites  de  Metaphysique. 

Posterity  has  not  adopted  the  high  opinion  which  Montmort 
here  expresses  respecting  the  physical  speculations  of  his  friend 
and  master ;  Malebranche  is  now  remembered  and  honoured  for 
his  metaphysical  works  alone,  Avhich  have  gained  the  following 
testimony  from  one  of  the  gi'eatest  critics  : 

As  a  thinker,  he  is  perhaps  the  most  profound  that  France  has 
ever  produced,  and  as  a  writer  on  i)liilosopliical  subjects,  there  is  not 
another  European  author  who  can  be  placed  before  him. 

Sir  William  Hamilton's  Lectures  on  Metaphysics,  Vol.  i.  page  262  ; 
see  also  his  edition  of  Reid's  Works,  page  266. 

218.  The  next  letter  is  from  Montmort  to  Nicolas  Bernoulli ; 
it  occupies  pages  3-52 — 360.  We  may  notice  that  Montmort  here 
claims  to  be  the  first  person  who  called  attention  to  the  theorem 
which  is  now  given  in  elementary  treatises  on  Algebra  under  the 
following  enunciation  :  To  find  the  number  of  terms  in  the  expan- 
sion of  any  multinomial,  the  exponent  being  a  positive  integer. 
See  Montmort's  page  355. 

219.  Montmort  gives  in  this  letter  some  examples  of  the  recti- 
fication of  curves ;  see  his  pages  35G,  357,  359,  360.  In  particular 
he  notices" one  which  he  had  himself  discussed  in  the  earty  days 
of  the  Integral  Calculus,  when,  as  he  says,  the  subject  was  well 
known  only  by  five  or  six  mathematicians.  This  example  is  the 
rectification  of  the  curve  called  after  the  name  of  its  inventor  De 
Beaune ;  see  John  Bernoulli's  works.  Vol.  I.  pages  62,  63.  AMiat 
Montmort  gives  in  this  letter  is  not  intelligible  by  itself,  but  it  can 
be  understood  by  the  aid  of  the  original  memoii*,  which  is  in  the 
Journal  des  Scavans,  Vol.  xxxi. 

These  remarks  by  Montmort  on  the  rectification  of  curves  are 
of  no  great  interest  except  to  a  student  of  the  history  of  the  Inte- 
gral Calculus,  and  they  are  not  free  from  errors  or  misprints. 


128  MONTMORT. 

220.  Montmort  quotes  the  following  sentence  from  a  letter 
written  by  Pascal  to  Format. 

Pour  vous  parler  francliement  de  la  Geometrie,  je  la  trouve  le  plus 
haut  exercice  de  I'espritj  mais  en  meme  temps  je  la  connois  pour  si 
invitile,  que  je  fais  peu  de  difference  entre  un  homme  qui  n'est  que 
Geometre  et  un  habile  Artisan;  aussi  je  I'appelle  le  plus  beau  metier 
du  monde;  mais  enfin  ce  n'est  qu'un  metier:  et  j'ai  souvent  dit  qu'elle 
est  bonne  pour  faire  I'essai,  mais  non  pas  I'emploi  de  notre  force. 

Montmort  naturally  objects  to  this  decision  as  severe  and  humi- 
liating, and  probably  not  that  which  Pascal  himself  would  have 
pronounced  in  his  earlier  days. 

221.  The  next  letter  is  also  from  Montmort  to  Nicolas  Ber- 
noulli; it  occupies  pages  361 — 370.  Montmort  says  he  has  just 
received  Do  Moivre's  book,  by  which  he  means  the  memoir  De 
Mensura  Sortis,  published  by  De  Moivre  in  the  Philosophical 
Transactions ;  and  he  proceeds  to  analyse  this  memoir.  Montmort 
certainly  does  not  do  justice  to  De  Moivre.  Montmort  in  fact 
considers  that  the  first  edition  of  his  own  work  contained  im- 
plicitly all  that  had  been  given  in  the  De  Mensura  Sortis;  and  he 
seems  almost  to  fancy  that  the  circumstance  that  a  problem  had 
been  discussed  in  the  correspondence  between  himself  and  the 
Bernoullis  was  sufficient  ground  to  deprive  De  Moivre  of  the  credit 
of  originality.  The  opinion  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli  was  far  more  favour- 
able to  De  Moivre ;  see  Montmort's  pages  862,  375,  378,  386. 

De  Moivre  in  his  Miscellanea  Analytica  replied  to  Montmort, 
as  we  shall  see  hereafter. 

222.  On  his  page  365  Montmort  gives  some  remarks  on  the 
second  of  the  five  problems  which  Huygens  proposed  for  solution ; 
see  Art.  35. 

Suppose  there  are  three  players ;  lot  a  be  the  number  of 
white  balls,  and  h  of  black  balls  ;  let  c  =  a-\-  h.  The  balls  are 
supposed  not  to  be  replaced  after  being  drawn ;  then  the  chance  of 
the  first  player  is 

a         h{h-V)  (h-2)a         b(h-l)  .,.(h-5)a 
,c+c(c-l)(c-2)(c-3)       c(c-l)  ...  (c-6)    '^ '" 


MONTMORT.  129 

Montmort  takes  credit  to  himself  for  summing  this  series,  so  as 
to  find  its  value  when  a  and  h  are  large  numbers ;  but,  without 
saying  so,  he  assumes  that  a  =  4.     Thus  the  series  becomes 

4l&f|c-l      \g-  ^     |c  — *7 


c 


\h_     '  |5-3  '  \h-Q 


Let  p  =  h  +  ^,  then  c=p+l]  thus  the  series  within  brackets 
becomes 

+  (p-(i)(p->7)(p-8)  +  ... 

Suppose  we  require  the  sum  of  n  terms  of  the  series.     The 
r^^  term  is 

(p-Sr  +  S)  (^-'3r  +  2)  (^^-3r  +  l)  ; 

assume  that  it  is  equal  to 

where  A,  B,  C,  D  are  to  be  independent  of  r. 
We  shall  find  that 

A=j>{p-  1)  {p  -  2), 
B=-(9/-4.5;>+()0), 
(7=54p-216, 
i>=-162. 

Hence  the  required  sum  of  n  terms  is 

np  (p  -  1)  {p  -  2)  -  '^^^  (V-  ^op  4-  60) 

n{n-l){n-^)  __  n  {n  -  1)  {n  -  2)  (7^  -  S) 

^         1.2.3  K'^W--^^)  1.2.3.4  ^'" 

This  result  is  sufficiently  near  Montmort's  to  shew  that  he  must 
have  adopted  nearly  the  same  method ;  he  has  fallen  into  some 
mistake,  for  he  gives  a  different  expression  for  the  terms  inde- 
pendent oip. 

In  the  problem  on  chances  to  which  this  is  subser\dent  we 

should  have  to  put  for  ?i  the  greatest  integer  in  -^ . 

9 


130  MONTMORT. 

Montmort  refers  on  his  page  364  to  a  letter  dated  June  8*^ 
1710,  which  does  not  appear  to  have  been  preserved. 

223.  The  next  letter  is  from  Nicolas  Bernoulli  to  Montmort ; 
it  occupies  pages  871 — 375.  Nicolas  Bernoulli  demonstrates  a 
property  of  De  Beaune's  curve  ;  he  also  gives  a  geometrical  recti- 
fication of  the  logarithmic  curve ;  but  his  results  are  very  in- 
correct. He  then  remarks  on  a  subject  which  he  says  had  been 
brought  to  his  notice  in  Holland,  and  on  which  a  memoir  had  been 
inserted  in  the  Philosophical  Transactions.  The  subject  is  the 
argument  for  Divine  Providence  taken  from  the  constant  regu- 
larity observed  in  the  births  of  both  sexes.  The  memoir  to  which 
Bernoulli  refers  is  by  Dr  John  Arbuthnot ;  it  is  in  Vol.  XXVII.  of 
the  Philosophical  Transactions,  and  was  published  in  1710.  Nicolas 
Bernoulli  had  discussed  the  subject  in  Holland  with  's  Gravesande. 

Nicolas  Bernoulli  says  that  he  was  obliged  to  refute  the  argu- 
ment. What  he  supposes  to  be  a  refutation  amounts  to  this  ;  he 
examined  the  registers  of  births  in  London  for  the  years  from  1629 
to  1710  inclusive;  he  found  that  on  the  average  18  males  were 
born  for  17  females.  The  greatest  variations  from  this  ratio  were 
in  1661,  when  4748  males  and  4100  females  were  born,  and  in 
1703,  when  7765  males  and  7683  females  were  born.  He  says 
then  that  we  may  bet  800  to  1  that  out  of  14,000  infants  the  ratio 
of  the  males  to  the  females  will  fall  within  these  limits ;  we  shall 
see  in  Art.  225  the  method  by  which  he  obtained  this  result. 

224.  The  next  letter  is  also  from  Nicolas  Bernoulli  to  Mont- 
mort ;  it  occupies  pages  875 — 887.  It  contains  some  remarks  on 
the  game  of  Her,  and  some  remarks  in  reply  to  those  made  by 
Montmort  on  De  Moivre's  memoir  De  Mensura  Soi'tis.  The  most 
impoj'tant  part  of  the  letter  is  an  elaborate  discussion  of  Walde- 
grave's  problem  ;  we  have  already  said  enough  on  this  problem, 
and  so  need  only  add  that  Nicolas  Bernoulli  speaks  of  this  discus- 
sion as  that  which  he  preferred  to  every  thing  else  which  he  had 
produced  on  the  subject;  see  page  881.  The  approbation  which 
he  thus  bestows  on  his  own  work  seems  well  deserved. 

225.  Thie  next  letter  is  also  from  Nicolas  Bernoulli  to  Mont- 
mort ;  it  occupies  pages   388 — 893.     It  is  entirely  occupied  with 


MONTMORT.  131 

the  question  of  the  ratio  of  male  infants  to  female  infants.  We 
have  already  stated  that  Nicolas  Bernoulli  had  refused  to  see  any 
argument  for  Divine  Providence  in  the  fact  of  the  nearly  constant 
ratio.  He  assumes  that  the  ])rohahility  of  the  hiHh  of  a  male  is  to 
the  probability  of  the  birth  of  a  female  as  IS  to  17  ;  he  then  shews 
that  the  chances  are  43  to  1  that  out  of  14,000  infants  the  males 
will  lie  between  7037  and  7363.  His  investigation  involves  a 
general  demonstration  of  the  theorem  of  his  uncle  James  called 
Bernoulli's  Theorem.  The  investigation  requires  the  summation 
of  terms  of  a  binomial  series  ;  this  is  effected  approximately  by  a 
process  which  is  commenced  in  these  words  :  Or  comme  ces  termes 
sont  furieusement  grands,  il  faut  un  artifice  singulier  pour  trouver 
ce  rapport  :  voici  comment  je  m'y  suis  pris. 

The  whole  investigation  bears  some  resemblance  to  that  of 
James  Bernoulli  and  may  have  been  suggested  by  it,  for  Nicolas 
Bernoulli  says  at  the  end  of  it,  Je  me  souviens  que  feu  mon  Oncle 
a  demontre  une  sembla])le  chose  dans  son  Traits  De  Arte  Con- 
jectandi,  qui  s'imprime  a  present  a  Bale,  . . . 

226.  TJie  next  letter  is  from  Montmort  to  Nicolas  Bernoulli ; 
it  occupies  pages  395 — 400.  Montmort  records  the  death  of  the 
Duchesse  d'Angouleme,  which  caused  him  both  grief  and  trouble  ; 
he  says  he  cannot  discuss  geometrical  matters,  but  will  confine 
himself  to  literary  intelligence. 

He  mentions  a  work  entitled  Pr emotion  Physique ^  ou  Action 
de  Dieu  sur  les  Creatures  demontree  par  raisonnement  The 
anonymous  author  pretended  to  follow  the  method  of  mathe- 
maticians, and  on  every  page  were  to  be  found  such  great  words 
as  Definition,  Axiom,  Theorem,  Demonstration,  Corollary,  &c. 

Montmort  asks  for  the  opinion  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli  and  his 
uncle  respecting  the  famous  Commerciiim  Epistolicum  which  he 
says  M™  de  la  Societe  Royale  ont  fait  imprimer  pour  assurer  a 
M.  Newton  la  gloire  d'avoir  invente  le  premier  et  seul  les  nou- 
velles  methodes. 

Montmort  speaks  with  approbation  of  a  little  treatise  which 
had  just  appeared  under  the  title  of  Mechanique  du  Feu. 

Montmort  expresses  his  strong  admiration  of  two  investigations 
which  he  had  received  from  Nicolas  Bernoulli ;  one  of  these  was 

9—2 


132  MONTMORT. 

the  solution  of  Waldegrave's  problem,  and  the  other  apparently 
the  demonstration  of  James  Bernoulli's  theorem :  see  Arts.  224,  225. 
Montmort  says,  page  400, 

Tout  cela  etoit  en  verite  bien  difficile  et  d'un  grand  travail. 
Yous  etes  ini  terrible  homme;  je  croyois  que  pour  avoir  pris  les  de- 
vants  je  ne  serois  pas  si-tot  ratrappe,  mais  je  vois  bien  que  je  me  suis 
trompe:  je  suis  a  present  bien  derriere  vous;  et  force  de  mettre  toute 
mon  ambition  a  vous  suivre  de  loin. 

227.  This  letter  from  Montmort  is  interesting,  as  it  records 
the  perplexity  in  which  the  writer  found  himself  between  the 
claims  of  the  rival  systems  of  natural  philosophy,  the  Cartesian 
and  the  Newtonian.     He  says,  page  397, 

Derange  comme  je  le  suis  par  I'autorite  de  M.  Newton,  et  d'un 
si  grand  nombre  de  sgavans  Geometres  Anglois,  je  serois  presque  tente 
de  renoncer  pour  jamais  a  I'etude  de  la  Physique,  et  de  remettre  a 
sgavoir  tout  cela  dans  le  Ciel;  mais  non,  I'autorite  des  plus  grands 
esprits  ne  doit  Y>oijit  nous  faire  de  loi  dans  les  clioses  oil  la  raison 
doit  decider. 

228.  Montmort  gives  in  this  letter   his   views  respecting  a 
History  of  Mathematics  ;  he  says,  page  399, 

II    seroit    a    soidiaiter    que    quelqu'un   voulut  prendre  la  peine  de 

nous  apprendre  comment  et  en  quel  ordre  les  decouvertes  en  Mathe- 

matiqucs  se  sont  succedees  les  unes  aux  autres,  et  h  qui  nous  en  avons 

r obligation.       On  a  fait  I'Histoire  de  la  Peinture,    de  la  Musique,  de 

la  Medecine,  &c.     line  bonne  Histoire  des  Matliematiques,  et  en  par- 

ticulier  de  la  Geometrie,  seroit  un  Ouvrage  beaucoup  plus  curieux  et 

plus  utile :  Quel  plaisir  n'auroit-on  pas  de  voir  la  liaison,  la  connexion 

des    raetliodes,  1' enchain  em  ent   des    difFerentes    theories,  a    commencer 

depuis  les  premiers  temps  jusqu'au    notre    ou    cette  science  se  trouve 

portee  a.  un  si  haut  degre    de    perfection.       II    me    semble    qu'un  tel 

Ouvrage  bien  fait  pourroit  etre  en  quelque  sorte  regarde  comme  I'his- 

toire  de  I'esprit  humaiiij     puisque  c'est  dans  cette  science  plus  qu'eu 

toute  autre  chose,  que  I'homme  fait    connoitre   I'excellence  de  ce  don 

d'intelligence  que  Dieu  lui  a  accorde  pour  I'clever  au  dessus  de  toutcs 

les  autres  Creatures. 


MONTMORT.  1.33 

Montmort  himself  had  made  some  progi'ess  in  the  work  which 
he  here  recommends;  see  Art.  137.  It  seems  however  that  his 
manuscripts  were  destroyed  or  totally  dispersed ;  see   Montucla, 

Ilistoire  des  Mathematiques  first  edition,  preface,  page  IX. 

229.  The  next  letter  is  from  Nicolas  Bernoulli  to  Montmort ; 
it  occupies  pages  401,  402.  Nicolas  Bernoulli  announces  that  the 
Ars  Conjectandi  has  just  been  published,  and  says,  II  n'y  aura 
gueres  rien  de  nouveau  pour  vous.  He  proposes  five  problems  to 
Montmort  in  return  for  those  which  Montmort  had  proposed  to 
him.  He  says  that  he  had  already  proposed  the  first  problem  in 
his  last  letter ;  but  as  the  problem  does  not  occur  before  in  the 
correspondence,  a  letter  must  have  been  suppressed,  or  a  portion 
of  it  omitted. 

The  third  problem  is  as  follows.  A  and  B  play  with  a  com- 
mon die,  A  deposits  a  crown,  and  B  begins  to  play ;  if  B  throws 
an  even  number  he  takes  the  crown,  if  he  throws  an  odd  number 
he  deposits  a  crown.  Then  A  throws,  and  takes  a  crown  if  he 
throws  an  even  number,  but  does  not  deposit  a  crown  if  he 
throws  an  odd  number.  Then  B  throws  again,  and  so  on.  Thus 
each  takes  a  crown  if  he  throws  an  even  number,  but  B  alone 
deposits  a  crown  if  he  throws  an  odd  number.  The  play  is  to 
continue  as  long  as  there  is  any  sum  deposited.  Determine  the 
advantage  of  A  or  B. 

The  fourth  problem  is  as  follows.  A  promises  to  give  to  B 
a  crown  if  B  with  a  common  die  throws  six  at  the  first  throw, 
two  crowns  if  B  throws  six  at  the  second  throw,  three  crowns 
if  B  throws  six  at  the  third  throw  ;  and  so  on. 

The  fifth  problem  generalises  the  fourth,  A  promises  to  give 
B  crowns  in  the  progression  1,  2,  4,  8,  16,  ...  or  1,  3,  9,  27,  ...  or 
1,  4,  9,  16,  25, ...  or  1,  8,  27,  64,  ...  instead  of  in  the  progression 
1,  2,  3,  4,  5,  as  in  the  fourth  problem. 

230.  The  next  letter  is  the  last;  it  is  from  Montmort  to 
Nicolas  Bernoulli,  and  it  occupies  pages  403—412.  It  enters 
largely  on  the  game  of  Her,  With  respect  to  the  five  problems 
proposed  to  him,  Montmort  says  that  he  has  not  tried  the  first 
and  second,  that  the  foTU'th  and  fifth  present  no  difticulty,  but 
that  the  third  is  much  more  difficult.     He  says  that  it  took  him 


134?  MONTMORT. 

a  long  time  to  convince  himself  that  there  would  be  neither 
advantage  nor  disadvantage  for  B,  but  that  he  had  come  to  this 
conclusion,  and  so  had  Waldegrave,  who  had  worked  with  him 
at  the  problem.  It  would  seem  however,  that  this  result  is 
obvious,  for  B  has  at  every  trial  an  equal  chance  of  winning  or 
losing  a  crown. 

Montmort  proposes  on  his  page  408  a  problem  to  Nicolas 
Bernoulli,  but  the  game  to  which  it  relates  is  not  described. 

231.  In  the  fourth  problem  given  in  Art.  229,  the  advantage 
of  B  is  expressed  by  the  series 

77  +  ^2  +  7^  +  pi  +  •  •  •  '^^^  infinitum. 

This  series  may  be  summed  by  the  ordinary  methods. 

We  shall  see  that  a  problem  of  the  same  kind  as  the  fourth 
and  fifth  of  those  communicated  by  Nicolas  Bernoulli  to  Mont- 
mort, was  afterwards  discussed  by  Daniel  Bernoulli  and  others,  and 
that  it  has  become  famous  under  the  title  of  the  Petersburg 
Problem. 

232.  Montmort's  work  on  the  whole  must  be  considered 
highly  creditable  to  his  acuteness,  perseverance,  and  energy.  The 
courage  is  to  be  commended  which  led  him  to  labour  in  a  field 
hitherto  so  little  cultivated,  and  his  example  served  to  stimulate 
his  more  distinguished  successor.  De  Moivre  was  certainly  far 
superior  in  mathematical  power  to  Montmort,  and  enjoyed  the 
great  advantage  of  a  long  life,  extending  to  more  than  twice  the 
duration  of  that  of  his  predecessor ;  on  the  other  hand,  the 
fortunate  circumstances  of  Montmort's  position  gave  him  that 
abundant  leisure,  which  De  Moivre  in  exile  and  poverty  must 
have  found  it  imj^jossible  to  secure. 


CHAPTER   IX. 


DE  MOIVRE. 


233.  Abraham  De  Moivre  was  bom  at  Vitri,  in  Cliampagne, 
in  1667.  On  account  of  the  revocation  of  the  edict  of  Nantes, 
in  1685,  he  took  shelter  in  England,  where  he  supported  himself 
by  giving  instruction  in  mathematics  and  answers  to  questions 
relatiuGf  to  chances  and  annuities.     He  died  at  London  in  1754. 

John  Bernoulli  speaks  thus  of  De  Moi^Te  in  a  letter  to 
Leibnitz,  dated  26  Apr.  1710;  see  page  847  of  the  volume  cited 
in  Art.  59  : 

...Dominus  Moy^Taeus,  insignis  certe  Geometra,  qui  liaud  dubie 
adluic  haeret  Loudini,  luctans,  ut  audio,  cum  fome  et  miseria,  quas  ut 
depellat,  victum  quotidianum  ex  informationibus  adolescentum  petere 
cogitur.  O  duram  sortein  hominis!  et  parum  aptam  ad  excitanda 
ingenia  nobilia;  quis  non  tandem  succumberet  sub  tam  iniquae  foi-tunae 
vexationibus  ?  vel  quodnam  ingenium  etiam  fervidissimum  non  algeat 
tandem  ?  Miror  certe  MoyvTaeum  tantis  angustiis  pressum  ea  tamen 
adhuc  praestare,  quae  praestat. 

De  Moivre  was  elected  a  Fellow  of  the  Royal  Society  in  1697 ; 
his  portrait,  strikingly  conspicuous  among  those  of  the  great 
chiefs  of  science,  may  be  seen  in  the  collection  which  adorns  the 
walls  of  the  apartment  used  for  the  meetings  of  the  Society.  It 
is  recorded  that  Newton  himself,  in  the  later  years  of  his  life, 
used  to  reply  to  inquirers  respecting  mathematics  in  these  words  : 
"  Go  to  Mr  De  Moivre,  he  knows  these  things  better  than  I  do." 
In  the  long  list  of  men  ennobled  by  genius,  virtue,  and  mis- 
fortune,  who   have   found   an  asvlum   in  England,  it  would  be 


18G  DE  MOIYRE. 

difficult   to   name  one  who  has  conferred   more   honour   on  his 
adopted  country  than  De  Moivre. 

234?.  Number  329  of  the  Philosophical  Transactions  consists 
entirely  of  a  memoir  entitled  De  Mensura  Soi^tis,  sen,  de  Probabili- 
tate  Eventuum  in  Ludis  a  Casu  Fortuito  Pendentihus.  Autore 
Abr.  De  Moivre,  RS.S. 

The  number  is  stated  to  be  for  the  months  of  January, 
February,  and  March  1711  ;  it  occupies  pages  213 — 261?  of  Vo- 
lume XXVII.  of  the  Philosophical  Transactions. 

The  memoir  was  afterwards  expanded  by  De  Moivre  into  his 
work  entitled  The  Doctrine  of  Chances:  or,  a  Method  of  Calculating 
the  Pi'ohabilities  of  Events  in  Play.  The  first  edition  of  this  work 
appeared  in  1718 ;  it  is  in  quarto  and  contains  xiv  +  175  pages, 
besides  the  title-leaf  and  a  dedication.  The  second  edition  appeared 
in  1738 ;  it  is  in  large  quarto,  and  contains  xiv  +  258  pages, 
besides  the  title-leaf  and  a  dedication  and  a  page  of  corrections. 
The  third  edition  appeared  in  1756,  after  the  author's  death  ;  it  is 
in  large  quarto,  and  contains  xii  +  348  pages,  besides  the  title-leaf 
and  a  dedication. 

235.  I  propose  to  give  an  account  of  the  memoir  De  Mensura 
Sortis,  and  of  the  third  edition  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances.  In  my 
account  of  the  memoir  I  shall  indicate  the  corresponding  parts  of 
the  Doctrine  of  Chances ;  and  in  my  account  of  the  Doctrine  of 
Chances  I  shall  give  such  remarks  as  may  be  suggested  by  compar- 
ing the  third  edition  of  the  work  with  those  which  preceded  it ; 
any  reference  to  the  Doctrine  of  Chances  must  be  taken  to  apply  to 
the  third  edition,  unless  the  contrary  is  stated. 

236.  It  may  be  observed  that  the  memoir  De  Mensura,  Sortis 
is  not  reprinted  in  the  abridgement  of  the  Philosophical  Transac- 
tions up  to  the  year  1800,  which  was  edited  by  Hutton,  Shaw,  and 
Pearson. 

The  memoir  is  dedicated  to  Francis  Robartes,  at  whose  recom- 
mendation it  had  been  drawn  up.  The  only  works  of  any  import- 
ance at  this  epoch,  which  had  appeared  on  the  subject,  were  the 
treatise  by  Huygens,  and  the  first  edition  of  Montmort's  book. 
De  Moivre  refers  to  these  in  words  which  we  have  already  quoted 
in  Art.  142. 


DE  MOIVRE.  137 

De  Moivre  says  that  Problems  16,  17,  18  in  his  memoir  were 
proposed  to  him  by  Robartes.     In  the  Preface  to  the  Doctrine  of 
Chances,  which  is  said  to  have  been  written  in  1717,  the  origin  of 
the  memoir  is  explained  in  the  following  words : 

'  Tis  now  about  Seven  Years,  since  I  gave  a  Specimen  in  the  Philo- 
sojyJiical  Transactions^  of  what  I  now  more  largely  treat  of  in  this  Book. 
The  occasion  of  my  then  undertaking  this  Subject  was  chiefly  owing  to 
the  Desire  and  Encouragement  of  the  Honourable  Francis  Robartes  Esq. 
(now  Earl  of  Kaclnor);  who,  upon  occasion  of  a  French  Tract,  called 
L Analyse  des  Jeux  de  Hazard,  which  had  lately  been  published,  was 
i)leased  to  propose  to  me  some  Problems  of  much  greater  difficulty  than 
any  he  had  found  in  that  Book ;  which  having  solved  to  his  Satisfaction, 
he  engaged  me  to  methodize  those  Problems,  and  to  lay  down  the  Pules 
which  had  led  me  to  their  Solution.  After  I  had  proceeded  thus  far,  it 
was  enjoined  me  by  the  Poyal  Society,  to  communicate  to  them  what  I 
had  discovered  on  this  Subject :  and  thereupon  it  was  ordered  to  be  i)ub- 
lished  in  the  Transactions,  not  so  much  as  a  matter  relating  to  Play,  but 
as  containing  some  general  Speculations  not  unworthy  to  be  considered 
by  the  Lovers  of  Truth. 

237.  The  memoir  consists  of  twenty-six  Problems,  besides 
a  few  introductory  remarks  which  exj^laiu  how  probability  is 
measured. 

238.  The  first  problem  is  to  find  the  chance  of  throwing  an 
ace  twice  or  oftener  in  eight  throws  with  a  single  die ;  see  Doctrine 
of  Chances,  page  13. 

239.  The  second  problem  is  a  case  of  the  Problem  of  Points. 
A  is  supposed  to  want  4  points,  and  B  to  want  G  points  ;  and  ^-I's 
chance  of  winning  a  single  point  is  to  ^'s  as  3  is  to  2  ;  see  Doctrine 
of  Chances,  page  18.  It  is  to  be  remembered  that  up  to  this  date, 
in  all  that  had  been  published  on  tlie  subject,  the  chances  of  the 
players  for  winning  a  single  point  had  always  been  assumed  equal ; 
see  Art.  173. 

240.  The  third  problem  is  to  determine  the  chances  of  A  and  B 
for  Avinning  a  single  game,  supposing  that  A  can  give  B  two  games 
out  of  three  ;  the  fourth  problem  is  of  a  similar  kind,  supjDosing 


138  BE   MOIVRE. 

that  A  can  give  B  one  game  out  of  three  :  see  Problems  I.  and  ii. 
of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances. 

24^1.  The  fifth  problem  is  to  find  how  many  trials  must  be 
made  to  have  an  even  chance  that  an  event  shall  happen  once  at 
least.     Montmort  had  already  solved  the  problem  ;  see  Art.  170. 

De  Moivre  adds  a  useful  approximate  formula  which  is  now  one 
of  the  permanent  results  in  the  subject;  we  shall  recur  to  it  in 
noticing  Problem  III.  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances,  where  it  is  repro- 
duced. 

242.  De  Moivre  then  gives  a  Lemma :  To  find  how  many 
Chances  there  are  upon  any  number  of  Dice,  each  of  them  of  the 
same  number  of  Faces,  to  throw  any  given  number  of  points  ;  see 
Doctrine  of  Chances,  page  89.  We  have  already  given  the  history 
of  this  Lemma  in  Art.  149. 

243.  The  sixth  problem  is  to  find  how  many  trials  must  be 
made  to  have  an  even  chance  that  an  event  shall  happen  twice  at 
least.  The  seventh  problem  is  to  find  how  many  trials  must  be 
made  to  have  an  even  chance  that  an  event  shall  happen  three 
times  at  least,  or  four  times  at  least,  and  so  on.  See  Problems  III. 
and  IV.  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances. 

244.  The  eighth  problem  is  an  example  of  the  Problem  of 
Points  with  three  players ;  it  is  Problem  VI.  of  the  Doctrine  of 
Chances. 

245.  The  ninth  problem  is  the  fifth  of  those  proposed  for 
solution  by  Huygens,  which  Montmort  had  enunciated  wrongly  in 
his  first  edition ;  see  Art.  199.  Here  we  have  the  first  publication 
of  the  general  formula  for  the  chance  which  each  of  two  players 
has  of  ruining  the  other  in  an  unlimited  number  of  games ;  see 
Art.  107.  The  problem  is  Problem  vil.  of  the  Doctrine  of 
Chances. 

246.  The  tenth  problem  is  Problem  viii.  of  the  Doctrine  of 
Chances,  where  it  is  thus  enunciated  : 

Two  Gamesters  ^  and  -5  lay  by  24  Counters,  and  play  with  three 
Dice,  on  this  condition ;  that  if  1 1  Points  come  np,  A  shall  take  one 


DE   MOIVRE.  139 

Counter  out  of  tlie  heap;  if  14,  ^  shall  take  out  one;  and  he  shall  be 
reputed  the  winner  who  shall  soonest  get  1 2  Counters. 

This  is  a  very  simple  problem.  De  Moivre  seems  quite  un- 
necessarily to  have  imagined  that  it  could  be  confounded  with  that 
which  immediately  preceded  it ;  for  at  the  end  of  the  ninth  pro- 
blem he  says, 

Maxime  cavendum  est  ne  Prohlemata  propter  speciem  aliquam 
affinitatis  inter  se  confundantur.  Problema  sequens  videtur  affine 
superiori. 

After  enunciating  his  ninth  problem  he  says, 

Problema  istud  a  superiore  in  hoc  diifert,  quod  23  ad  pluriraum 
tesserarum  jactibus,  ludus  necessano  finietur ;  cum  Indus  ex  lege  supe- 
rioris  problematis,  posset  in  aeternum  continuari,  propter  reciproca- 
tionem  lucri  et  jacturse  se  invicem  perpetuo  destruentium. 

247.  The  eleventh  and  twelfth  problems  consist  of  the  second 
of  those  proposed  for  solution  by  Huygens,  taken  in  two  mean- 
ings ;  they  form  Problems  X.  and  XI.  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances. 
The  meanings  given  by  De  Moivre  to  the  enunciation  coincide 
with  the  first  and  second  of  the  three  considered  by  James  Ber- 
noulli ;  see  Arts.  35  and  199. 

248.  The  thirteenth  problem  is  the  first  of  those  proposed  fur 
solution  by  Huygens ;  the  fourteenth  problem  is  the  fourth  of  the 
same  set :  see  Art.  35.  These  problems  are  very  simple  and  are 
not  repeated  in  the  Doctrine  of  Chances.  In  solving  the  fourth  of 
the  set  De  Moivre  took  the  meaning  to  be  that  A  is  to  draw  three 
white  balls  at  least.  Montmort  had  taken  the  meaning  to  be  that 
A  is  to  draw  exactly  three  white  balls.  John  Bernoulli  in  his 
letter  to  Montmort  took  the  meaning  to  be  that  A  is  to  draw  three 
white  balls  at  least.  James  Bernoulli  had  considered  both  mean- 
ings.    See  Art.  199. 

249.  The  fifteenth  problem  is  that  which  we  have  called 
Waldegrave's  problem;  see  Art.  211.  De  Moivre  here  discusses 
the  problem  for  the  case  of  three  players  :  this  discussion  is  re- 
peated, and  extended  to  the  case  of  four  players,  in  the  Doctrine  of 
Chances,  pages  132 — 159.  De  Moivre  was  the  first  in  publishing  a 
solution  of  the  problem. 


140  DE  MOIVRE. 

250.  The  sixteenth  and  seventeenth  problems  relate  to  the 
game  of  bowls ;  see  Art.  177.  These  problems  are  reproduced  in 
a  more  general  form  in  the  Doctrine  of  Chances,  pages  117 — 123. 
Respecting  these  two  problems  Montmort  says,  on  his  page  366, 

Les  Problemes  16  et  17  ne  sont  que  deux  cas  tres  simples  d'un 
meme  Probleme,  c'est  presque  le  seul  qui  m'ait  echape  de  tous  ceux  que 
je  trouve  dans  ce  Livre. 

251.  The  eighteenth  and  nineteenth  problems  are  Problems 
XXXIX.  and  XL.  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances,  where  we  shall  find 
it  more  convenient  to  notice  them. 

252.  The  remaining  seven  problems  of  the  memoir  form 
a  distinct  section  on  the  Duration  of  Play.  They  occur  as 
Problems  LViii,  LX,  LXi,  LXii,  LXiii,  Lxv,  LXVI,  of  the  Doctrine 
of  Chances;  and  we  shall  recur  to  them. 

253.  It  will  be  obvious  from  what  we  have  here  given  that  the 
memoir  De  Mensura  Sortis  deserves  especial  notice  in  the  history 
of  our  subject.  Many  important  results  were  here  first  published 
by  De  Moivre,  although  it  is  true  that  these  results  already  existed 
in  manuscript  in  the  Ars  Conjectandi  and  the  correspondence 
between  Montmort  and  the  Bernoullis. 

We  proceed  to  the  Doctrine  of  Chances. 

254.  The  second  edition  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances  contains 
an  Advertisement  relating  to  the  additions  and  improvements 
effected  in  the  work ;  this  is  not  reprinted  in  the  third  edition. 
The  second  edition  has  at  the  end  a  Table  of  Contents  which 
neither  of  the  others  has.  The  third  edition  has  the  following 
Advertisement : 

The  Author  of  this  Work,  by  the  failure  of  his  Eye-sight  in  extreme 
old  age,  was  obUged  to  entrust  the  Care  of  a  new  Edition  of  it  to  one  of 
his  Eriends ;  to  whom  he  gave  a  Copy  of  the  former,  with  some  marginal 
Corrections  and  Additions,  in  his  own  hand  writing.  To  these  the 
Editor  has  added  a  few  more,  where  they  were  thought  necessary :  and 
has  disposed  the  whole  in  better  Order;  by  restoring  to  their  proper 
places  some  things  that  had  been  accidentally  misplaced,  and  by  putting 
all  the  Problems  concerning  Aymuities  together;  as  they  stand  in  the 
late  imj-yroved  edition  of  the  Treatise  on  that  Subject.      An  A'ppendix 


DE  MOIVRE.  14:1 

of  several  useful  Articles  is  likewise  subjoined  :  the  whole  according 
to  a  Plan  concerted  with  the  Author,  above  a  year  before  his  death. 

255.  The  following  list  will  indicate  the  parts  which  are  new 
in  the  third  edition.  The  Remark,  pages  30 — 33 ;  the  Remark, 
pages  48,  49 ;  the  greater  part  of  the  second  Corollary,  pages  64 — 66; 
the  Examples,  page  88 ;  the  Scholium,  page  95  ;  the  Remark, 
page  116;  the  third  Corollary,  page  138;  the  second  Corollary, 
page  149  ;  the  Remark,  pages  151 — 159  ;  the  fourth  Corollary, 
page  162;  the  second  Corollary,  pages  176  — 179;  the  Note 
at  the  foot  of  page  187  ;  the  Remark,  pages  251 — 254. 

The  part  on  life  annuities  is  very  much  changed,  according  to 
the  plan  laid  down  in  the  Advertisement. 

In  the  second  and  third  editions  the  numbers  of  the  Problems 
agree  up  to  Problem  xi ;  Problem  xii.  of  the  third  edition  had 
been  Problem  Lxxxix.  of  the  second ;  from  Problem  xii.  to 
Problem  LXix.  of  the  third  edition  inclusive,  the  number  of  each 
Problem  exceeds  by  unity  its  number  in  the  second  edition ;  Pro- 
blem LXIX.  of  the  second  edition  is  incorporated  in  the  third 
edition  with  Problem  VI ;  Problems  LXX.  and  LXXI.  are  the 
same  in  the  two  editions,  allowing  for  a  misprint  of  LXXI.  for  LXX. 
in  the  second  edition.  After  this  the  numbering  differs  consider- 
ably because  in  the  second  edition  Problems  respecting  life  annui- 
ties are  not  separated  from  the  other  Problems  as  they  are  in  the 
third  edition. 

The  first  edition  of  the  work  was  dedicated  to  Newton  :  the 
second  was  dedicated  to  Lord  Carpenter,  and  the  dedication  of  the 
second  edition  is  reprinted  at  the  beginning  of  the  third  ;  the 
dedication  to  Newton  is  reprinted  on  page  329  of  the  third  edition. 

256.  The  first  edition  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances  has  a  good 
preface  explaining  the  design  and  utility  of  the  book  and  giving  an 
account  of  its  contents ;  the  preface  is  reproduced  in  the  other 
editions  with  a  few  omissions.  It  is  to  be  regretted  that  the  fol- 
lowing paragraphs  were  not  retained,  which  relate  respectively  to 
the  first  and  second  editions  of  Montmort's  work  : 

However,  had  I  allowed  my  self  a  little  more  time  to  consider  it, 
I  had  certainly  done  the  Justice  to  its  Author,  to  have  owned  that  he 
had  not  only  illustrated  Buy  gens' s  Method  by  a  gi'cat  variety  of  well 


142  DE  MOIVRE. 

chosen  Examples,  but  tliat  be  bad  added  to  it  several  curious  things  of 
bis  own  Invention. 


Since  the  printing  of  my  Specimen,  Mr.  de  Monmort,  Author  of  the 
Analyse  des  jeux  de  Hazard^  Published  a  Second  Edition  of  that  Book, 
in  which  he  has  particularly  given  many  proofs  of  his  singular  Genius, 
and  extraordinary  Capacity;  which  Testimony  I  give  both  to  Truth, 
and  to  the  Friendship  with  which  he  is  pleased  to  Honour  me. 

The  concluding  paragraph  of  the  preface  to  the  first  edition 
refers  to  the  Ars  Conjectandi,  and  invites  Nicolas  and  John  Ber- 
noulli to  prosecute  the  subject  begun  in  its  fourth  part ;  this 
paragraph  is  omitted  in  the  other  editions. 

We  repeat  that  we  are  about  to  analyse  the  third  edition  of  the 
Doctrine  of  Chances,  only  noticing  the  previous  editions  in  cases  of 
changes  or  additions  in  matters  of  importance. 

257.  The  Doctrine  of  Chances  begins  with  an  Introduction  of 
S3  pages,  which  explains  the  chief  rules  of  the  subject  and  illus- 
trates them  by  examples  ;  this  part  of  the  work  is  very  much  fuller 
than  the  corresponding  part  of  the  first  edition,  so  that  our  remarks 
on  the  Introduction  do  not  apply  to  the  first  edition.  De  Moivre 
considers  carefully  the  following  fundamental  theorem  :  suppose 
that  the  odds  for  the  happening  of  an  event  at  a  single  trial  are  as 
a  to  h,  then  the  chance  that  the  event  will  happen  r  times  at  least 
in  n  trials  is  found  by  taking  the  first  n  —  r-i-1  terms  of  the  expan- 
sion of  (a  +  hy  and  dividing  by  (a  +  by.  We  know  that  the  result 
can  also  be  expressed  in  another  manner  corresponding  to  the 
second  formula  in  Art.  172 ;  it  is  curious  that  De  Moivre  gives 
this  without  demonstration,  though  it  seems  less  obvious  than 
that  which  he  has  demonstrated. 

To  find  the  chance  that  an  event  may  happen  just  r  times,  De 
Moivre  directs  us  to  subtract  the  chance  that  it  will  happen  at  least 
r—1  times  from  the  chance  that  it  will  happen  at  least  r  times. 
He  notices,  but  less  distinctly  than  we  might  expect,  the  modern 
method  which  seems  more  simple  and  more  direct,  by  which  we 
begin  with  finding  the  chance  that  an  event  shall  happen  jvst  r 
times  and  deduce  the  chance  that  it  shall  happen  at  least  r 
times. 


DE  MOIVRE.  113 

258.  De  Moivre  notices  the  advantage  arising  from  employing 
a  single  letter  instead  of  two  or  three  to  denote  the  probaljility  of 
the  happening  of  one  event.  Thus  if  x  denote  the  probability  of 
the  happening  of  an  event,  \  —x  will  denote  the  probability  of  its 
failing.  So  also  y  and  z  may  denote  the  probabilities  of  the  hap- 
pening of  two  other  events  respectively.     Then,  for  example, 

x{\-y){\-z) 

will  represent  the  probability  of  the  first  to  the  exclusion  of  the 
other  two.  De  Moivre  says  in  conclusion,  '^  and  innumerable  cases 
of  the  same  nature,  belonging  to  any  number  of  Events,  may  be 
solved  without  any  manner  of  trouble  to  the  imagination,  by  the 
mere  force  of  a  proper  notation." 

259.  In  his  third  edition  De  Moivre  draws  attention  to  the 
convenience  of  approximating  to  a  fraction  with  a  large  numerator 
and  denominator  by  continued  fractions,  which  he  calls  "the 
Method  proposed  by  Dr  Wallis,  Hiiygens,  and  others."  He  gives 
the  rule  for  the  formation  of  the  successive  convergents  which  is 
now  to  be  found  in  elementary  treatises  on  Algebra ;  this  rule  he 
ascribes  to  Cotes. 

2G0.  The  Doctrine  of  Clicuices  contains  7-i  problems  exclusive 
of  those  relating  to  life  annuities ;  in  the  first  edition  there  were 
53  problems. 

261.  We  have  enunciated  Problems  I.  and  ii.  in  Art.  240. 
Suppose  p  and  q  to  represent  the  chances  of  A  and  ^  in  a  single 
game.    Problem  I.  means  that  it  is  an  even  chance  that  A  "wall  win 

1  1 

three  o^ames  before  B  wins  one  :  thus  p^  =  cv-    Hence  x>  =  -^^^  ,  and 

7  =  1  —  7777 .     Problem  li.  means  that  it  is  an  even  chance  that  A 

will  win  three  games  before  B  wins  two.    Thus  p^  +  Aip^q  =  ^  ;  which 

must  be  solved  by  trial. 

These  problems  are  simple  examples  of  the  general  formula  in 
Art.  172. 


262.     Problems  ill,  IV,  and  V.  are  included  in  the  followin 


144  DE  MOIVRE. 

general  enunciation.     Suppose  a  the  number  of  chances  for  the 
happening  of  an  event  in  a  single  trial,  and  h  the  number  of 
chances  for  its  failing :  find  how  many  trials  must  be  made  to  have 
an  even  chance  that  the  event  will  happen  r  times  at  least.    . 
For  example,  let  r  =  1. 

Suppose    X  the  number    of   trials.      Then    the    chance   that 

If 
the  event  fails  x  times  in  succession  is  -. tt^  .     And  by  suppo- 
sition this  is  equal  to  the  chance  of  its  happening  once  at  least 
in   X  trials.      Therefore    each    of  these    chances   must   be   equal 

to  -X .    Thus 

2 

}f  1 


{a  +  hy      2  ' 
from  this  equation  x  may  be  found  by  logarithms. 

De  Moivre  proceeds  to  an  approximation.     Put  -  =  q.     Thus 


X  log  [  1  4-  - )  =  log  2. 


If  ^  =  1,  we  have  x=l.     If  5'  be  gi'eater  than  1,  we  have  by 


expanding  log  (  1  +  -  J , 


where  log  2  will  mean  the  logarithm  to  the  Napierian  base.    Then 
if  q  be  large  we  have  approximately 

7 

x=  q  log  2  =  zTTzq  nearly. 

De  Moivre  says,  page  87, 

Thus  we  have  assigned  the  very  narrow  limits  within  which  the  ratio 
of  £c  to  q  is  comprehended ;  for  it  begins  with  unity,  and  terminates  at 
last  in  the  ratio  of  7  to  10  very  near. 

But  X  soon  converges  to  the  limit  0.7^',  so  that  this  value  of  x  may 
be  assumed  in  all  cases,  let  the  value  of  q  be  what  it  will. 

The  fact  that  this  result  is  true  when  q  is  moderately  large  is  the 


DE  MOIVRE.  145 

element  of  truth  in  the  mistake  made  by  M.  de  Mdre  ;  he  assumed 
that  such  a  result  should  hold  for  all  values  of  q  :  see  Art.  14. 

263.  As  another  example  of  the  general  enunciation  of 
Art.  262,  let  r  =  S. 

The  chance  that  the  event  will  happen  at  least  3  times  in  x 
trials  is  equal  to  the  first  x  —  2  terms  of  the  expansion  of 


a  h 


X 


+ 


\a  +  b     a  +  bj  * 
and  this  chance  by  hypothesis  is  - .     Hence  the  last  three  terms 

of  the  expansion  will  also  be  equal  to  ^ ,  that  is, 

W  +  xV-'  a  +  ^^^  I'-'' «'  =  I  («  +  W' 

If  ^  =  1  we  find  x  =  o. 

X 

If  q  be  supposed  indefinitely  great,  and  we  put  -  =  z,  we  get 

where  e  is  the  base  of  the  Napierian  logarithms. 

By  trial  it  is  found  that  2  =2675  nearly.     Hence  De  Moivre 
concludes  that  x  always  lies  between  oq  and  2675(;^. 

264.     De  Moivre  exhibits  the  following  table  of  results  ob- 
tained in  the  manner  shewn  in  the  two  preceding  Ai'ticles. 

A  Table  of  the  Limits. 

The  Value  of  x  will  always  be 

For  a  single  Event,  between  \q  and  O'GOSg'. 
For  a  double  Event,  between  2)q  and  l-GTS^-. 
For  a  triple  Event,  between  5q  and  2  675^. 
For  a  quadruple  Event,  between  ^q  aud  2>(dl2q. 
For  a  quintuple  Event,  between  9^'  and  i-GTO^-. 
For  a  sextuple  Event,  between  \\q  and  b-ij^Sq. 
ka. 

10 


146  DE  MOIVRE. 

And  if  the  number  of  Events  contended  for,  as  well  as  the  number 

q  be  pretty  large  in  respect  to  Unity;  the  number  of  Trials  requisite  for 

....     ^n—\  .       , 

those  Events  to  happen  n  times  will  be  — ^  q^  or  barely  nq. 

De  Moivre  seems  to  have  inferred  the  general  result  enun- 
ciated in  the  last  sentence,  from  observing  the  numerical  values 
obtained  in  the  six  cases  which  he  had  calculated,  for  he  gives  no 
further  investigation. 

265.  In  Art.  263  we  have  seen  that  De  Moivre  concludes 

that  -  always  lies  between  5  and  2"675.     This  may  appear  very 

probable,  but  it  is  certainly  not  demonstrated.  It  is  quite  con- 
ceivable, in  the  absence  of  any  demonstration  to  the  contrary,  that 

-  should  at  first  increase  with  q,  and  so  be  greater  than  5,  and 

then  decrease  and  become  less  than  2  675,  and  then  increase 
again  to  its  limit  2-675.  The  remark  applies  to  the  general  pro- 
position, whatever  be  the  value  of  r,  as  well  as  to  the  particular 
example  in  which  r  =-  3. 

It  would  not  be  very  easy  perhaps  to  shew  from  such  an 
equation  as  that  in  Art.  263,  that  x  increases  continually  with  q ; 
and  yet  from  the  nature  of  the  question  we  may  conclude  that 
this  must  be  the  case.  For  if  the  chance  of  success  in  a  single 
trial  is  diminished,  it  appears  obvious  that  the  number  of  trials 
must  be  increased,  in  order  to  secure  an  even  chance  for  the  event 
to  happen  once  at  least. 

266.  On  pages  39 — 43  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances,  we  have 
the  Lemma  of  which  we  have  already  given  an  account ;  see 
Art.  242. 

267.  Problem  VI.  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances  is  an  example 
of  the  Problem  of  Points  with  three  players.  De  Moivre  gives 
the  same  kind  of  solution  as  Fermat :  see  Arts.  16  and  18.  In 
the  third  edition  there  is  also  a  discussion  of  some  simple  cases 
according  to  the  method  which  Pascal  used  for  two  players  ;  see 
Art.  12.  De  Moivre  also  gives  here  a  good  rule  for  solving  the 
problem   for   any   number   of  players ;    the   rule   is  founded   on 


DE   MOIVRE.  147 

Fermat's  metliod,  and  is  intended  to  lighten  as  mucli  as  possible 
the  labour  which  must  be  incurred  in  applying  the  method  to 
complex  cases.  The  rule  was  first  published  in  the  Miscellanea 
Analytica,  in  1730;  it  is  given  in  the  second  edition  of  the 
Doctrine  of  Chances  on  pages  191,  192. 

2G8.  Problem  vii.  is  the  fifth  of  those  proposed  by  Huygens 
for  solution ;  see  Art.  35.  We  have  already  stated  that  De  Moivre 
generalises  the  problem  in  the  same  way  as  James  Bernoulli, 
and  the  result,  with  a  demonstration,  was  first  published  in  the 
De  Mensura  Sortis ;  see  Arts.  107,  245.  De  Moivre's  demon- 
stration is  very  ingenious,  but  not  quite  complete.  For  he  finds 
the  ratio  of  the  chance  that  A  will  ruin  B  to  the  chance  that 
B  will  ruin  A  ;  then  he  assumes  in  effect  that  in  the  lonof  nm 
one  or  other  of  the  players  must  be  ruined :  thus  he  deduces 
the  absolute  values  of  the  two  chances. 

See  the  first  Appendix  to  Professor  De  Morgan's  Essay  on 
Prohahilities  in  the  Cabinet  Cyclopcedia. 

We  have  spoken  of  Problem  viii.  in  Art.  246. 

269.     Problem  ix.  is  as  follows. 

Supposing  A  and  B,  whose  proportion  of  skill  is  as  a  to  6,  to  play 
together,  till  A  either  wins  the  number  q  of  Stakes,  or  loses  the  number 
;;  of  them ;  and  that  B  sets  at  every  Game  the  sum  G  to  the  sum  L ;  it 
is  required  to  find  the  Advantage  or  Disadvantage  of  ^. 

This  was  Problem  XLIII.  of  the  first  edition  of  the  Doctrine 
of  Chances,  in  the  preface  to  which  it  is  thus  noticed : 

The  43d  Problem  having  been  proposed  to  me  by  Mr.  Thomas  Wood- 
cock, a  Gentleman  whom  I  infinitely  respect,  I  attempted  its  Solution 
with  a  very  great  desire  of  obtaining  it;  and  having  had  the  good 
Fortune  to  succeed  in  it,  I  returned  him  the  Solution  a  few  Days  after 
he  was  pleased  to  jn-opose  it.  This  Problem  is  in  my  Opinion  one  of 
the  most  curious  that  can  be  propos'd  on  this  Subject ;  its  Solution 
containing  the  Method  of  determining,  not  only  that  Advantage  which 
results  from  a  Superiority  of  Chance,  in  a  Play  confined  to  a  certain 
number  of  Stakes  to  be  won  or  lost  by  either  Party,  but  also  that  which 
may  result  from  an  unequality  of  Stakes ;  and  even  compares  those  two 
Advantages  together,  when  the  Odds  of  Chance  being  on  one  side,  the 
Odds  of  Money  are  on  the  other. 

10—2 


148  DE  MOIVRE. 

In  the  Miscellanea  Analytica,  page  204,  the  problem  is  again 
said  to  have  been  proposed  by  Thomas  Woodcock,  sjyectatissimo 
viro,  but  he  is  not  mentioned  in  the  second  or  third  edition  of 
the  Doctrine  of  Chances ;  so  that  De  Moivre's  infinite  respect  for 
him  seems  to  have  decayed  and  disappeared  in  a  finite  time. 

The  solution  of  the  problem  is  as  follows : 

Let  R  and  S  respectively  represent  the  Probabilities  which  A  and  B 
have  of  winning  all  the  Stakes  of  their  Adversary ;  which  Probabilities 
have  been  determined  in  the  vii*^  Problem.  Let  us  first  suppose  that 
the  Sums  deposited  by  A  and  B  are  equal,  viz.  G,  and  G  :  now  since  A 
is  either  to  win  ihe  sum  qG,  or  lose  the  sum  pG,  it  is  plain  that  the  Gain 
of  A  ought  to  be  estimated  by  EqG  —  SpG;  moreover  since  the  Sums 
deposited  are  G  and  G,  and  that  the  proportion  of  the  Chances  to  win 

one  Game  is  as  a  to  h,  it  follows  that  the  Gain  of  A  for  each  individual 

aQ  _  hQ 

Game  is ^ —  j    and  for  the  same  reason  the  Gain  of  each  individual 

a  +  0 

aG  —  hL 
Game  would  be  j-  ,    if  the  Suras  deposited  bv  A  and  B  were  re- 

spectively  L  and  G.  Let  us  therefore  now  suppose  that  they  are  L 
and  Gj  then  in  order  to  find  the  whole  Gain  of  A  in  this  second  cir- 
cumstance, we  may  consider  that  whether  A  and  B  lay  down  equal 
Stakes  or  unequal  Stakes,  the  Probabilities  which  either  of  them  has 
of  winning  all  the  Stakes  of  the  other,  sufier  not  thereby  any  alter- 
ation, and  that  the  Play  will  continue  of  the  same  length  in  both  cir- 
cumstances before  it  is  determined  in  favour  of  either;  wherefore  the 
Gain  of  each  individual  Game  in  the  first  case,  is  to  the  Gain  of  each 
individual  Game  in  the  second,  as  the  whole  Gain  of  the  first  case,  to 
the  whole  Gain  of  the  second;  and  consequently  the  whole  Gain  of  the 

/-7  7    7- 

second  case  will  be  Rq  -^px or  restoring  the  values  of  H  and  >S', 

a  —  b  °  ' 


qa^xa^-b^-pb^xa'^-b^         i..  -,.    -,  ,      aG-bL 
^^^,_f^^, multiplied  by     ^_^    . 

270.  In  the  first  edition  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances, 
pages  136 — 142,  De  Moivre  gave  a  very  laborious  solution  of  the 
preceding  Problem.  To  this  was  added  a  much  shorter  solution, 
communicated  by  Nicolas  Bernoulli  from  his  uncle.  This  solution 
was  founded  on  an  artifice  which  De  Moivre  had  himself  used  in 


DE  MOIVRE.  14y 

the  ninth  problem  of  the  De  Mensura  Sortis.  De  Moivre  how- 
ever renounces  for  himself  the  claim  to  the  merit  of  the  solu- 
tion. This  renunciation  he  repeats  in  the  Miscellanea  Analytica, 
page  206,  where  he  names  the  author  of  the  simple  solution 
which  we  have  already  given.     He  says, 

Ego  vere  illucl  ante  libenter  fassus  sum,  idque  ipsum  etiamnum 
libenter  fateor,  quamvis  solutio  Problematis  mei  noni  causam  fortasse 
dederit  hiijus  solutionis,  me  tamen  nihil  juris  in  eam  habere,  eamque 
CI.  ilhus  Autori  ascribi  lequum  esse. 

Septem  aut  octo  abliinc  annis  D.  Stevens  Int.  Tempi.  Socius,  Yir 
ingenuus,  singulari  sagacitate  prseditus,  id  sibi  propositum  habens  ut 
Problema  superius  allatum  solveret,  hac  ratione  solutionem  facile  asse- 
cutus  est,  quam  mihi  his  verbis  exhibuit. 

Then  follows  the  solution,  after  which  De  Moivre  adds, 

Doctissimus  adolescens  D.  Cranmei',  apud  Genevenses  MatliematicaB 
Professor  dignissiraus,  cujus  recordatio  seque  ac  Collegae  ejus  i)eritissimi 
D.  Calandrin  mihi  est  perjucunda,  cum  superiore  anno  Londini  com- 
moraretur,  narravit  milii  se  ex  Uteris  D.  Nic.  Bernoulli  ad  se  datis  acce- 
pisse  CI.  Yirum  novam  solutionem  hujus  Problematis  adeptum  esse, 
quani  prioribus  autor  anteponebat ;  cum  vcro  nihil  de  via  solutionis 
dixerit,  si  mihi  conjicere  liceat  qualis  ea  sit,  banc  opinor  eandem  esse 
atque  illam  quam  raodo  attuli. 

271.  We  have  already  spoken  of  Problems  x.  and  xi.  in 
Art.  247.  In  his  solution  of  Problem  x.  De  Moivre  uses  the 
theorem  for  the  summation  of  series  to  which  we  have  refen^ed 
in  Art.  152.  A  corollary  was  added  in  the  second  edition  and 
was  expanded  in  the  third  edition,  on  which  we  Avill  make  a 
remark. 

Suppose  that  A,  B,  and  C  throw  in  order  a  die  of  n  faces, 
and  that  a  faces  are  favourable  to  A,  and  h  to  B,  and  c  to  (7, 
where  a  ■\-  h  +  c  =  n.  Required  the  chances  wdiich  A,  B,  and  G 
have  respectively  of  being  the  first  to  throw  a  corresponding  face. 
It  may  be  easily  shewn  that  the  chances  are  proportional  to 
air,  (h  +  c)  hn,  and  (h  +  c)  {a  +  c)  c,  respectively.  De  Moivre,  in 
his  third  edition,  page  Qo,  seems  to  imply  tliat  before  the  order 
was  fixed,  the  chances  would  be  proportional  to  ^,  h,  c.  This 
must  of  course  mean  that  such  would  be  the  case  if  there  were 


150  DE  MOIVRE. 

no  order  at  all;  that  is  if  the  die  were  to  be  thrown  and  the 
stake  awarded  to  A,  B,  or  C,  according  as  the  face  which  appeared 
was  one  of  the  a,  h,  c  respectively.  If  there  is  to  be  an  order, 
but  the  order  is  as  Hkely  to  be  one  as  another,  the  result  will  be 
different.  The  chance  of  A  for  example  will  be  one  sixth  of  the 
sum  arising  from  six  possible  and  equally  likely  cases.  It  will  be 
found  that  A's  chance  is 


a 


{6a'  +  9a(h-i-c)  +  S  (h'  +  c')  +  She} 
Q{n'-{b  +  c)  (c  +  a)  (a  +  h)} 

272.  Problem  xii.  appeared  for  the  first  time  in  the  second 
edition,  page  24^8,  with  this  preliminary  notice.  ''A  particular 
Friend  having  desired  of  me  that  to  the  preceding  Problems  I 
would  add  one  more,  I  have  thought  fit  to  comply  with  his  desire ; 
the  Problem  was  this."  The  problem  is  of  no  great  importance  ; 
it  is  solved  by  the  method  often  used  in  the  Ai^s  Co7vjectandi, 
which  we  have  explained  in  Art.  106. 

273.  Problem  xiii.  relates  to  the  game  of  Bassette,  and 
Problem  XIV.  to  the  game  of  Pharaon;  these  problems  occupy 
pages  69 — 82  of  the  work.  We  have  already  sufficiently  noticed 
these  games ;  see  Arts.  154,  168.  De  Moivre's  discussion  is  the 
same  in  all  his  three  editions,  except  that  a  paragraph  on  page  37 
of  the  first  edition,  extending  from  the  words  "Those  who  are  ..." 
to  the  end  of  the  page,  is  omitted  in  the  following  editions. 
The  paragraph  is  in  fact  an  easy  example  of  the  formulae  for  the 
game  of  Bassette. 

274.  Problems  XV.  to  XX.  form  a  connected  series.  De  Moivre 
solves  simple  examples  in  chances  and  applies  his  results  to  esta- 
blish a  Theory  of  Permutations  and  Combinations  ;  in  modern 
times  we  usually  adopt  the  reverse  order,  establish  the  Theory  of 
Permutations  and  Combinations  first,  and  afterwards  apply  the 
theory  in  the  discussion  of  chances.  We  will  take  an  example  of 
De  Moivre's  method  from  his  Problem  XV.  Suppose  there  are 
six  things  a,  h,  c,  d,  e,  f,  and  let  two  of  them  be  taken  at  random  ; 
required  the  chance  that  a  shall  stand  first,  and  h  second.     The 


DE  MOIVRE.  151 

1 

chance  of  taking  a  first  is  ^ ;  and  tliere  are  then  five  things  left, 

and  the  chance  of  now  taking  5  is  ^ .     Therefore  the  required 

chance  is  -^ .     Then  De  Moivre  says, 

Since  the  taking  a  in  the  first  i)lace,  and  h  in  the  second,  is  hut  one 
single  Case  of  those  by  which  six  Things  may  change  their  order,  being 
taken  two  and  two ;  it  follows  that  the  number  of  Changes  or  Permu- 
tations of  six  Things,  taken  two  and  two,  must  be  30. 

275.     In  his  Preface  De  Moivre  says, 

Having  explained  the  common  Rules  of  Combinations,  and  given  a 
Theorem  which  may  be  of  use  for  the  Solution  of  some  Problems  re- 
lating to  that  Subject,  I  lay  down  a  new  Theorem,  which  is  properly  a 
contraction  of  the  former,  whereby  several  Questions  of  Chance  are 
resolved  with  wonderful  ease,  tho'  the  Solution  might  seem  at  first  sight 
to  be  of  insuperable  difiiculty. 

The  mil}  Theorem  amounts  to  nothing  more  than  the  simplifi- 
cation of  an  expression  by  cancelling  factors,  which  occur  in  its 
numerator  and  denominator ;  see  Doctrine  of  Chances,  pages  ix.  89. 

27C.  Problems  xxi.  to  XXV.  consist  of  easy  applications  to 
questions  concerning  Lotteries  of  the  principles  established  in  the 
Problems  xv.  to  XX. ;  only  the  first  two  of  these  questions  con- 
cerning Lotteries  appeared  in  the  first  edition. 

A  Scholium  is  given  on  page  95  of  the  third  edition  which 
deserves  notice.  De  Moivre  quotes  the  following  formula :  Sup- 
pose a  and  n  to  be  positive  integers  ;  then 

1111  1 

-  +  — r-T  +  — -^  +  — 7-i.  +  ...+ 


n     n-\-l      71  +  2     ?i  +  3  a  —  1 

_       a       1        1       A  (l^      1\      B  (1       r 

~  ^""^7^  +  2;^ ""  2^  "^  2  \n'  "  ^;  "^  I  W      a\ 

where  A=\.    ^^'W     ^=A'  - 


152  DE  MOIVRE. 

As  De  Moivre  says  A,  B,  (7,  ...  are  "the  numbers  of  Mr.  James 
Bernoulli  in  his  excellent  Theorem  for  the  Summing  of  Powers." 
See  Art.  112.  De  Moivre  refers  for  the  demonstration  of  the 
formula  to  the  Supplement  to  the  Miscellanea  Analytica,  where 
the  formula  first  appeared.  We  shall  recur  to  this  in  speaking  of 
the  Miscellanea  Analytica. 

277.  Problems  xxvii.  to  xxxil.  relate  to  the  game  of  Quad- 
rille ;  although  the  game  is  not  described  there  is  no  difficulty  in 
understanding  the  problems  which  are  simple  examples  of  the 
Theory  of  Combinations :  these  problems  are  not  in  the  first 
edition. 

278.  Problem  xxxiil.  is  To  find  at  Pharaon  how  much  it  iiT 
that  the  Banker  gets  per  Cent  of  all  the  Money  that  is  adventured. 
De  Moivre  in  his  Preface  seems  to  attach  great  importance  to  this 
solution ;  but  it  scarcely  satisfies  the  expectations  which  are  thus 
raised.  The  player  who  stakes  against  the  bank  is  in  fact  sup- 
posed to  play  merely  by  chance  without  regard  to  what  would  be 
his  best  course  at  any  stage  of  the  game,  although  the  previous 
investigations  of  Montmort  and  De  Moivre  shewed  distinctly  that 
some  courses  were  far  less  pernicious  than  others. 

The  Banker's  adversary  in  De  Moivre's  solution  is  therefore 
rather  a  machine  than  a  gambler  with  liberty  of  choice. 

279.  Problem  xxxiv.  is  as  follows  : 

Supposing  A  and  £  to  play  together,  that  the  Chances  they  have 
respectively  to  win  are  as  a  to  6,  and  that  B  obliges  himself  to  set  to  A 
so  long  as  A  wins  without  interruption  :  what  is  the  advantage  that  A  gets 
by  his  hand? 

The  result  is,  supposing  each  to  stake  one, 

Itj  1  ^  +  ^ + FTi)^  +  ^TTif  +  •  •  • '"  *"-^'"'^"™  } ' 

that  is,  — = — . 

0 

280.  Problems  xxxv.  and  xxxvi.  relate  to  the  game  dis- 
cussed by  Nicolas  Bernoulli  and  Montmort,  which  is  called  Treize 
or  Rencontre;  see  Art.  162. 


DE  MOIVRK.  153 

De  Moivre  treats  the  subject  with  great  ingenuity  and  with 
more  generality  than  his  predecessors,  as  we  shall  now  shew. 

281.     Problem  xxxv.  is  thus  enunciated  : 

Any  number  of  Letters  a,  h,  c,  d,  e,/,  &c.,  all  of  them  different, 
being  taken  promiscuously  as  it  happens :  to  find  the  Probability  that 
some  of  them  shall  be  found  in  their  places  according  to  the  rank  they 
obtain  in  the  Alphabet;  and  that  others  of  them  shall  at  the  same  time 
be  displaced. 

Let  n  be  the  number  of  the  letters ;  suppose  that  j)  specified 
letters  are  to  be  in  their  places,  q  specified  letters  out  of  their 
places,  and  the  remaining  n  —p  —  q  letters  free  from  any  restric- 
tion.    The  chance  that  this  result  will  happen  is 


n{n—l)...(n—j)+l)\       1  n—p         1.2      (n— p)(?i— ^  — 1) 
This  supposes  that  p  is  greater  than  0 ;  if  ^  =  0,  the  result  is 

Iw"^     1.2       n{n-l)      '" 

If  we  suppose  in  this  formula  q=^m  —  1,  we  have  a  result  akeady 
implicitly  given  in  Art.  IGl. 

In  demonstrating  these  formulae  De  Moivre  is  content  to  ex- 
amine a  few  simple  cases  and  assume  that  the  law  which  presents 
itself  will  hold  universally.     We  will  indicate  his  method. 

The  chance  that  a  is  in  the  first  place  is  - ;  the  chance  that  a  is 

in  the  first  place,  and  h  in  the  second  place  is  — , — -:r^  :  hence  the 

^  ^  n{n—i) 

chance  that  a  is  in  the  first  place  and  h  not  in  the  second  place  is 

1  1 

n     n  (ii  —  1)  * 

Similarly  the  chance  that  a,  h,  c  are  all  in  their  proper  places  is 
1 


/       IN  /  — K^  ;  subtract  this  from  the  chance  that  a  and  h  are  in 
n  [71  —  1)  (n  —  2) ' 

their  proper  places,  and  we  have  the  chance  that  a  and  h  are  in 
their  proper  places,  and  c  not  in  its  proper  place  :  thus  this  chance  is 

1  1 


n 


(n  -  1)      n  («.  -  1)  {n  -  2) 


15^  DE  MOIVRE. 

De  Moivre  uses  a  peculiar  notation  for  facilitating  this  process. 
Let  +  a  denote  the  chance  that  a  is  in  its  proper  place  and  —  a  the 
chance  that  it  is  out  of  it ;  let  +  J  denote  the  chance  that  h  is  in 
its  proper  place  and  —  h  the  chance  that  it  is  out  of  it ;  and  so  on. 
And  in  general  let  such  a  symbol  as  -\-  a-\-h  -\-  c  —  d  —  e  denote  that 
a,  h,  c  are  in  their  proper  places,  and  d,  e  out  of  theirs. 

n       '     n(n  -1)       '      n{n  —  l)(n  —  2) 

1 ^ 

n(n-l){n-2){n-B)~'^'"' 

Then  we  have  the  following  results  : 

+  h        =r 

+  h  +  a  =  s 

+  h  —  a  =  r—s  (1) 

+c+h        =s 
+  c-\-h  +  a  =  t 

+  c  +  h-a  =  s-t •. (2) 

+  c  -  a        =r-s  by  (1) 

+  c -  a  +  J  =        s-t     by  (2) 

+  c-a-b=        r-2s  +  t (3) 

+d+c+h        =t 

■Yd+G^-h-{-a  =  v 

+  d  +  c-\-h-a  =  t-v (4) 

+  J+c-a        ^s-t  by  (2) 

+  c?+c  —  a  +  &=        t  —  v     by  (4) 

■\-d-\-c-a-h=        s-2t^v (5) 

■\-d-h-a       =r-2s-\-t  by  (3) 

-\-d—h  —  a-\-c=  s-2t-\-v      by  (5) 

d  —  h  —  a  —  c—  r— 35 +  8^—1? (6) 

It  is  easy  to  translate  into  words  any  of  these  S3rmbolical  pro- 
cesses.    Take  for  example  that  which  leads  to  the  result  (2) : 


DE   MOIYRE.  155 

this  means  that  the  chance  that  c  and  h  are  in  their  proper  places 
is  s  ;  and  this  we  know  to  be  true  ; 

-\-  c-\-'b-\-  a  =  t, 

this  means  that  the  chance  that  c,  h,  a  are  all  in  their  proper 
places  is  t ;  and  this  we  know  to  be  true. 

From  these  two  results  we  deduce  that  the  chance  that  c  and  h 
are  in  their  proper  places,  and  a  out  of  its  place  is  5  —  ^ ;  and  this 
is  expressed  symbolically  thus, 

-{-c-\-h  —  a  =  s  —  t 

Similarly,  to  obtain  the  result  (8) ;  we  know  from  the  result  (1) 
that  r  —  5  is  the  chance  that  c  is  in  its  proper  place,  and  a  out  of 
its  proper  place ;  and  we  know  from  the  result  (2)  that  5  —  /5  is  the 
chance  that  c  and  h  are  in  their  proper  places,  and  a  out  of  its  pro- 
per place  ;  hence  we  infer  that  the  chance  that  c  is  in  its  proper 
place,  and  a  and  h  out  of  their  proper  places  is  r  —  2s  +  ^ ;  and  this 
result  is  expressed  symbolically  thus, 

282.  De  Moivre  refers  in  his  Preface  to  this  process  in  the  fol- 
lowing terms : 

111  the  3oth  and  36th  Problems,  I  explain  a  new  sort  of  Algebra, 
whereby  some  Questions  relating  to  Combinations  are  solved  by  so  easy 
a  Process,  that  their  Solution  is  made  in  some  measure  an  immediate 
consequence  of  the  Method  of  Notation.  I  will  not  pretend  to  say  that 
this  new  Algebra  is  absolutely  necessary  to  the  Solving  of  those  Ques- 
tions which  I  make  to  depend  on  it,  since  it  appears  that  Mr.  Montmort, 
Author  of  the  Analyse  cles  Jeux  de  Hazard,  and  Mr.  Nicholas  Bernoulli 
have  solved,  by  another  Method,  many  of  the  cases  therein  proposed : 
But  I  hope  I  shall  not  be  thought  guilty  of  too  much  Confidence,  if 
I  assure  the  Reader,  that  the  Method  I  have  followed  has  a  degree  of 
Simplicity,  not  to  say  of  Generality,  which  will  hardly  be  attained  by 
any  other  Steps  than  by  those  I  have  taken. 

283.  De  Moi^Te  himself  enunciates  his  result  verbally  ;  it  is  of 
course  equivalent  to  the  formula  which  we  have  given  in  Art.  281, 
but  it  will  be  convenient  to  reproduce  it.  The  notation  being  that 
already  explained,  he  says, 


loG  DE  MOIVRE. 

...tlien  let  all  the  quantities  I,  r,  s,  f,v,  &c.  be  written  down  with 
Signs  alternately  positive  and  negative,  beginning  at  1,  if])  be  =  0;  at  r, 
if^9  be  =  1;  at  5,  if  p  be  =  2;  &c.  Prefix  to  these  Quantities  the  Co- 
efficients of  a  Binomial  Power,  whose  index  is  =  q;  this  being  done, 
those  Quantities  taken  all  together  will  express  the  Probability  re- 
quired. 

284.  The  enunciation  and  solution  of  Problem  xxxvi.  are  as 
follows : 

Any  given  number  of  Letters  a,  h,  c,  d,  e,  /,  &c.,  being  each  repeated 
a  certain  number  of  times,  and  taken  promiscuously  as  it  happens  :  To 
find  the  Probability  that  of  some  of  those  sorts,  some  one  Letter  of  each 
may  be  found  in  its  place,  and  at  the  same  time,  that  of  some  other 
sorts,  no  one  Letter  be  found  in  its  place. 

Suppose  n  be  the  number  of  all  the  Letters,  I  the  number  of  times 

that  each  Letter  is  repeated,  and  consequently  j  the  whole  number  of 

Sorts :  supj)ose  also  that  p  be  the  number  of  Sorts  of  which  some  one 
Letter  is  to  be  found  in  its  place,  and  q  the  number  of  Sorts  of  which 
no  one  Letter  is  to  be  found  in  its  place.  Let  now  the  prescriptions 
given  in  the  preceding  Problem  be  followed  in  all  respects,  saving  that 

r  must  here  be  made  =  — ,  s  =  —, =^-  ,     t  —  — ; 7T-7 777  ,  &c.,  and 

n  n  {ii  —  1)  n  {n  —1)  [71  —  2) 

the  Solution  of  any  particular  case  of  the  Problem  will  be  obtained. 

Thus  if  it  were  required  to  find  the  Probability  that  no  Letter  of  any 

sort  shall  be  in  its  place,  the  Probability  thereof  would  be  expressed  by 

the  Series 

^     ^"^^     1.2     ^  1.2.3        ^  1.2.3.4  '^'^''• 

of  which  the  number  of  Terms  is  equal  to  q+  1. 

But  in  this  particular  case  q  would  be  equal  to  -j ,  and  therefore,  the 
foregoing  Series  might  be  changed  into  this,  viz. 

1  n-l       I  {n-l){n-2l)       1   {71-I)  {n-2l)  (n-Sl) 

2  n-l       6  {n  -  1)  {n  -  2)  '^  24:  (n-l)  {n  -  2)  (n  -  3)   '^* 

of  which  the  number  of  Terms  is  equal  to  — j—  . 


DE  MOIVRE.  loT 

285.  De  Moivre  then  adds  some  Corollaries.  The  follo^\ing 
is  the  first  of  them  : 

From,  hence  it  follows,  that  the  Probability  of  one  or  more  Letters, 
indeterminately  taken,  being  in  their  places,  will  be  expressed  as  fol- 
lows : 

_  1  iij-l     1   ill  -  I)  {n  -  21)  _  j_  {n  -l)(n-  21)  {n  -  3Q 
2  n-1^  ^\r-1){ji-2)       24<    (n- 1)  {n-2)  (n-S) 

This  agrees  with  what  we  have  already  given  from  Nicolas 
Bernoulli ;  see  Art.  204. 

In  the  next  three  Corollaries  De  Moivre  exhibits  the  pro- 
bability that  two  or  more  letters  should  be  in  their  places,  that 
three  or  more  should  be,  and  that  four  or  more  should  be. 

286.  The  four  Corollaries,  which  we  have  just  noticed,  are 
examples  of  the  most  important  part  of  the  Problem;  this  is 
treated  by  Laplace,  who  gives  a  general  formula  for  the  proba- 
bility that  any  assigned  number  of  letters  or  some  greater  number 
shall  be  in  their  proper  places.  Theorie. .  .des  Proh.  pages  217 — 222. 
The  part  of  Problems  xxxv.  and  xxxvi.  which' De  Moivi-e  puts 
most  prominently  forward  in  his  enunciations  and  solutions  is 
the  condition  that  p  letters  are  to  be  in  their  places,  q  out  of 
their  places,  and  n  —  ij  —  q  free  from  any  restriction ;  this  part 
seems  peculiar  to  De  MoIato,  for  we  do  not  find  it  before  his  time, 
nor  does  it  seem  to  have  attracted  attention  since. 

287.  A  Remark  is  given  on  page  116  which  was  not  in  the 
preceding  editions  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances.  De  Moivre  shews 
that  the  sum  of  the  series 

111 

1  —  o  +  ^  "  oT  +  •  •  •  wi  infinitum, 

is  equal  to  unity  diminished  by  the  reciprocal  of  the  base  of  the 
Napierian  logarithms. 

288.  The  fifth  Corollary  to  Problem  xxxvi.  is  as  follows  : 

If  A  and  B  each  holding  a  Pack  of  Cards,  pull  them  out  at  the  same 
time  one  after  another,  on  condition  tliat  every  time  two  like  Cards  are 


158  DE  MOIVRE. 

pulled  out,  A  shall  give  B  a  Guinea;  and  it  were  required  to  find  what 
consideration  £  ought  to  give  A  to  play  on  those  Terms :  the  Answer 
will  be  one  Guinea,  let  the  number  of  Cards  be  what  it  will. 

Altho'  this  be  a  Corollary  from  the  preceding  Solutions,  yet  it  may 
more  easily  be  made  out  thus ;  one  of  the  Packs  being  the  Rule  where- 
by to   estimate  the  order  of  the  Cards  in  the  second,  the  Probability 

that  the  two  first  Cards  are  alike  is  — ,    the  Probability  that  the  two 


1^ 

52 


second  are  alike  is  also  -^ ,  and  therefore  there  being  52  such  alike  com- 


52 
binations,  it  follows  that  the  value  of  the  whole  is  r-::  ==  1. 

52 

It  may  be  interesting  to  deduce  this  result  from  the  formulae 
already  given.  The  chance  that  out  of  ti  cards,  2^  specified  cards 
will  be  in  their  places,  and  all  the  rest  out  of  their  places  will 
be  obtained  by  making  q=  n  —p  in  the  first  formula  of  Art.  281. 
The  chance  that  cmy  p  cards  will  be  in  their  places,  and  all  the 
rest  out  of  their  places  will  be  obtained  by  multiplying  the  pre- 

ceding  result  by  - — ^= .      And  since  in  this  case  B  receives 

\n  —  p  I  p 

p  guineas,  we  must  multiply  by  p  to  obtain  5's  advantage.     Thus 
we  obtain 


p-l  \  '2      [3  '   [^ 


n  —  p 


Denote  this  by  <^  {p)  ;  then  we  are  to  shew  that  the  sum  of 
the  values  of  <^  {p)  obtained  by  giving  to  p  all  values  between 
1  and  n  inclusive  is  unity. 

Let  y^r  (ti)  denote  the  sum  ;  then  it  may  be  easily  shewn  that 

'f(n  +  l)-'f  {71)  =  0. 

Thus  -yjr  (n)  is  constant  for  all  values  of  n ;  and  it  =  1  when 
71  =  1,  so  that  -^  {71)  is  always  =  1. 

289.     The  sixth  Corollary  to  Problem  xxxvi.  is  as  follows : 
If  the  number  of  Packs  be  given,  the  Probability  that  any  given 
number  of  Circumstances  may  happen  iu  any  number  of  Packs,  will 


DE  MOIVRE.  159 

easily  be  found  by  our  Metliod  :  thus  if  tbe  number  of  Packs  be  ^,  the 
Probability  that  one  Card  or  more  of  the  same  Suit  and  Name  in  every 
one  of  the  Packs  may  be  in  the  same  position,  will  be  expressed  as  fol- 
lows, 

1  1  1 


n'-"     2[n(n-  l)]'''  '  [3  {w  (ji  -  1)  (w  -  2)]^-^ 

1 


[4  [n  (71-1)  {n-2)  (n-S)\ 


—,  &c. 


k-2. 


Laplace  demonstrates  this  result;  see  Theorie  . . .  des  Prob. 
page  224. 

290.  Problems  xxxvii.  and  xxxviii.  relate  to  the  game  of 
Bowls;  see  Arts.  177,  250. 

De  Moivre  says,  page  120, 

Having  given  formerly  the  Solution  of  this  Problem,  proposed  to  me 
by  the  Honourable  Francis  Rohartes,  Esq;,  in  the  FhilosopTiical  Trans- 
actions Number  329;  I  there  said,  by  way  of  Corollary,  that  if  the 
proportion  of  Skill  in  the  Gamesters  were  given,  the  Problem  might 
also  be  solved :  since  w^hich  time  M.  de  Monmort^  in  the  second  Edition 
of  a  Book  by  him  published  upon  the  Subject  of  Chance,  has  solved 
this  Problem  as  it  is  extended  to  the  consideration  of  the  Skill,  and 
to  carry  his  Solution  to  a  great  number  of  Cases,  giving  also  a  Me- 
thod whereby  it  might  be  carried  farther:  But  altlio'  his  Solution  is 
good,  as  he  has  made  a  right  use  of  the  Doctrine  of  Combinations, 
yet  I  think  mine  has  a  greater  degree  of  Simplicity,  it  being  deduced 
from  the  original  Principle  whereby  I  have  demonstrated  the  Doctrine 
of  Permutations  and  Combinations:... 

291.  Problems  xxxix.  to  XLil.  form  a  connected  set.  Pro- 
blem XXXIX.  is  as  follows  : 

To  find  the  Expectation  of  A,  when  with  a  Die  of  any  given  num- 
ber of  Paces,  he  undertakes  to  fling  any  number  of  them  in  any  given 
number  of  Casts. 

Let  j9  -f  1  be  the  number  of  faces  on  the  die,  n  the  number 
of  casts, /the  number  of  faces  which  A  undertakes  to  fling.  Then 
-4's  expectation  is 


ICO  DE  MOIVKE. 


{p  +  1)" 


(_p+l)"_/^«  +  /01^(^_l)» 


_/(/-lK/-2)(^_,)„^.. 

Be  Moivre  infers  this  general  result  from  the  examination 
of  the  simple  cases  in  which  f  is  equal  to  1,  %  8,  4  respec- 
tively. 

He  says  in  his  Preface  respecting  this  problem, 

When  I  began  for  the  first  time  to  attempt  its  Solution,  I  had 
nothing  else  to  guide  me  but  the  common  Kules  of  Combinations,  such 
as  they  had  been  delivered  by  Dr.  Wallis  and  others;  which  when  I 
endeavoured  to  apply,  I  was  surprized  to  find  that  my  Calculation 
swelled  by  degrees  to  an  intolerable  Bulk :  For  this  reason  I  was  forced 
to  turn  my  Views  another  way,  and  to  try  whether  the  Solution  I 
was  seeking  for  might  not  be  deduced  from  some  easier  considerations; 
whereupon  I  happily  fell  upon  the  Method  I  have  been  mentioning, 
which  as  it  led  me  to  a  very  great  Simplicity  in  the  Solution,  so  I 
look  upon  it  to  be  an  Improvement  made  to  the  Method  of  Com- 
binations. 

The  problem  has  attracted  much  attention;  we  shall  find  it 
discussed  by  the  following  writers  :  Mallet,  Acta  Helvetica,  1772 ; 
Euler,  Opuscula  Analytica,  Vol.  ii.  1785;  Laplace,  Memoir es.., 
2Mr  clivers  Savans',  1774,  Theorie...  cles  Proh.  page  191 ;  Trembley, 
Memoires  de  V Acad...  Berlin,  1794,  1795. 

We  shall  recur  to  the  problem  when  we  are  giving  an  account 
of  Euler's  writings  on  our  subject. 

292.     Problem  XL.  is  as  follows : 

To  find  in  how  many  Trials  it  will  be  probable  that  A  with  a  Die 
of  any  given  number  of  Faces  shall  throw  any  proposed  number  of 
them. 

1 

Take  the  formula  given  in  Art.  291,  suppose  it  equal  to  ^  , 

and  seek  for  the  value  of  n.  There  is  no  method  for  solving 
this  equation  exactly,  so  De  Moivre  adopts  an  approximation. 
He  supposes  that  ^  +  1,  ^,  ^  —  1,  j9  —  2, are  in  Geometrical 


DE  MOIYRE.  161 

Progression,  which  supposition  he  says   "will  very  little  err  from 
the  truth,  especially  if  the  proportion  of  ^  to  1,  be  not  very  small." 

Put  r  for ;  thus  the  equation  becomes 

P 

1      /  1     /(/- 1)    1      /(/-  1)  (/-  2)  2_  .        ^1. 
1?^""^     1.2      r'''  \S  r''''^'"      2' 

that  is  ^1__)=2. 

Hence  -■   =  1  _  f  _  ]   , 

and  then  n  may  be  found  by  logarithms. 

De  Moivre  says  in  his  Preface  respecting  this  problem, 

The  40th  Problem  is  the  reverse  of  the  preceding;  It  contains  a 
very  remarkable  Method  of  Solution,  the  Artifice  of  which  consists 
in  changing  an  Arithmetic  Progression  of  Numbers  into  a  Geometric 
one;  this  being  always  to  be  done  when  the  Numbers  are  large,  and 
their  Intervals  small.  I  freely  acknowledge  that  I  have  been  indebted 
long  ago  for  this  useful  Idea,  to  my  much  respected  Friend,  That  Ex- 
cellent Mathematician  Dr.  Halley,  Secretary  to  the  Royal  Society, 
whom  I  have  seen  practise  the  thing  on  another  occasion:  For  this 
and  other  Instructive  Notions  readily  imparted  to  me,  during  an  un- 
interrupted Friendship  of  five  and  Twenty  years,  I  return  him  my 
very  hearty  Thanks. 

Laplace  also  notices  this  method  of  approximation  in  solving 
the  problem,  and  he  compares  its  result  with  that  furnished  by  his 
own  method  ;  see  Theorie  ...  des  Proh.  pages  198 — 200. 

293.     Problem  XLI.  is  as  follows  : 

Supposing  a  regular  Prism  having  a  Faces  marked  i,  h  Faces 
marked  ii,  c  Faces  marked  iii,*  d  Faces  marked  iv,  kc.  what  is  the 
Probability  that  in  a  certain  number  of  throws  n,  some  of  the  Faces 
marked  i  will  be  thrown,  as  also  some  of  the  Faces  marked  ii  ? 

This  is  an  extension  of  Problem  xxxix ;  it  was  not  in  the  first 
edition  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances. 

Let  a  +  h  ■{-  c  -{■  d  +  ...=s\  then  the  Probability  required 
will  be 


1  [,"  _  {(,  _  „). + (,  _  j)«j  +  {s-a-  in 


11 


162:  BE  MOIVRE. 

If  it  be  required  that  some  of  the  Faces  marked  I,  some  of 
the  Faces  marked  ii,  and  some  of  the  Faces  marked  ill  be 
thrown,  the  ProbabiUty  required  will  be 

-f  (s-a-hy+  {s-h-cy+{s-c-ay 

—  {s  —  a  —  h  —  cy 

And  so  on  if  other  Faces  are  required  to  be  thrown. 

De  Moivre  intimates  that  these  results  follow  easily  from  the 
method  adopted  in  Problem  xxxix. 

294.  Problem  XLII.  first  appeared  in  the  second  edition ; 
it  is  not  important. 

Problem  XLiil.  is  as  follows  : 

Any  number  of  Chances  being  given,  to  find  the  Probability  of  their 
being  produced  in  a  given  order,  without  any  limitation  of  the  number 
of  times  in  which  they  are  to  be  produced. 

It  may  be  remarked  that,  for  an  approximation,  De  Moivre 
proposes  to  replace  several  numbers  representing  chances  by  a 
common  mean  value ;  it  is  however  not  easy  to  believe  that  the 
result  would  be  very  trustworthy.  This  problem  was  not  in  the 
first  edition. 

295.  Problems  XLiv.  and  XLV.  relate  to  what  we  have  called 
Waldegrave's  Problem  ;  see  Art.  211. 

In  De  Moivre's  first  edition,  the  problem  occupies  pages  77 — 102. 
De  Moivre  says  in  his  preface  that  he  had  received  the  solution 
by  Nicolas  Bernoulli  before  his  own  was  published  ;  and  that  both 
solutions  were  printed  in  the  PhilosojyJiical  Transactions,  No.  341. 
De  Moivre's  solution  consists  of  a  very  full  and  clear  discussion 
of  the  problem  when  there  are  three  players,  and  also  when  there 
are  four  players ;  and  he  gives  a  little  aid  to  the  solution  of  the 
general  problem.  The  last  page  is  devoted  to  an  explanation  of  a 
method  of  solving  the  problem  which  Brook  Taylor  communicated 
to  De  Moivre. 

In  De  Moivre's  third  edition  the  problem  occupies  pages  132 — 159. 
The  matter  given  in  the  first  edition  is  here  reproduced,  omitting, 


DE   MOIVRE.  163 

however,  some  details  which  the  reader  might  be  expected  to  fill 
up  for  himself,  and  also  the  method  of  Brook  Taylor.  On  the 
other  hand,  the  last  nine  pages  of  the  discussion  in  the  third 
edition  were  not  in  the  first  edition ;  these  consist  of  explanations 
and  investigations  with  the  view  of  enabling  a  reader  to  determine 
numerical  results  for  any  number  of  players,  supposing  that  at 
any  stage  it  is  required  to  stop  the  play  and  divide  the  money 
deposited  equitably.  This  part  of  the  problem  is  peculiar  to 
De  Moivre. 

The  discussions  which  De  Moivre  gives  of  the  particular 
cases  of  three  players  and  four  players  are  very  easy  and  satis- 
factory ;  but  as  a  general  solution  his  method  seems  inferior  to 
that  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli.  We  may  remark  that  the  investigation 
for  three  players  given  by  De  Moivre  will  enable  the  student  to 
discover  how  Montmort  obtained  the  results  which  he  gives  with- 
out demonstration  for  three  players ;  see  Art.  209.  De  Moivre 
determines  a  pla^^er's  expectation  by  finding  first  the  advantage 
resulting  from  his  chance  of  winning  the  whole  sum  deposited,  and 
then  his  disadvantage  arising  from  the  contributions  which  he 
may  have  had  to  make  himself  to  the  whole  sum  deposited ;  the 
expectation  is  obtained  by  subtracting  the  second  result  from  the 
first.  Montmort  determined  the  expectation  by  finding,  first  the 
advantage  of  the  player  arising  from  his  chance  of  winning  the 
deposits  of  the  other  two  players,  and  then  the  disadvantage 
arising  from  the  chance  which  the  other  two  players  have  of 
winning  his  deposits ;  the  expectation  is  obtained  by  subtracting 
the  second  result  from  the  first. 

The  problem  will  come  before  us  again  as  solved  by  Laplace. 

296.  Problem  XLVI.  is  on  the  game  of  Hajzard;  there  is  no 
description  of  the  game  here,  but  there  is  one  given  by  Montmort 
on  his  page  177 ;  and  from  this  description,  De  Moivre's  solution 
can  be  understood :  his  results  agree  with  Montmort's.  Pro- 
blem XLVII.  is  also  on  Hazard ;  it  relates  to  a  point  in  the  game 
which  is  not  noticed  by  Montmort,  and  it  is  only  from  De  Moivre's 
investigation  itself  that  we  can  discover  wliat  the  problem  is, 
which  he  is  considering.    With  respect  to  this  problem,  De  Moivre 

says,  page  165, 

11—2 


164<  DE  MOIVRE. 

After  I  had  solved  the  foregoing  Problem,  which  is  about  12  years 
ago,  I  spoke  of  my  Solution  to  Mr.  Henry  Stuart  Stevens^  but  with- 
out communicating  to  him  the  manner  of  it:  As  he  is  a  Gentleman 
who,  besides  other  uncommon  Qualifications,  has  a  particular  Sagacity 
in  reducing  intricate  Questions  to  simple  ones,  he  brought  me,  a  few 
days  after,  his  Investigation  of  the  Conclusion  set  down  in  my  third 
Corollary;  and  as  I  have  had  occasion  to  cite  him  before,  in  another 
Work,  so  I  here  renew  with  pleasure  the  Expression  of  the  Esteem 
which  I  have  for  his  extraordinary  Talents  : 

Then  follows  the  investigation  due  to  Stevens.  The  above 
passage  occurs  for  the  first  time  in  the  second  edition,  page  140  ; 
the  name  however  is  there  spelt  Stephens :  see  also  Art.  270. 

Problem  XLVII.  is  not  in  the  first  edition ;  on  the  other  hand, 
a  table  of  numerical  values  of  chances  at  Hazard,  without  ac- 
companying explanations,  is  given  on  pages  V7%  175  of  the  first 
edition,  which  is  not  reproduced  in  the  other  editions. 

297.  Problems  XLVIII.  and  XLix.  relate  to  the  game  of  Raffling. 
If  three  dice  are  thrown,  some  throws  will  present  triplets,  some 
doublets,  and  some  neither  triplets  nor  doublets;  in  the  game 
of  Raffles  only  those  throws  count  which  present  triplets  or 
doublets.  The  game  was  discussed  by  Montmort  in  his 
pages  207 — 212 ;  but  he  is  not  so  elaborate  as  De  Moivre.  Both 
writers  give  a  numerical  table  of  chances,  which  De  Moivre  says  was 
drawn  up  by  Francis  Eobartes,  twenty  years  before  the  publica- 
tion of  Montmort's  work  ;  see  Miscellanea  Analytica,  page  224. 

Problem  XLIX.  was  not  in  De  Moivre's  first  edition,  and 
Problem  XLVIII.  was  not  so  fully  treated  as  in  the  other  edi- 
tions. 

298.  Problem  L.  is  entitled  Of  Whisk;  it  occupies  pages  172 — 179. 
This  is  the  game  now  called  Whist.  De  Moivre  determines  the 
chances  of  various  distributions  of  the  Honouy^s  in  the  game.  Thus, 
for  example,  he  says  that  the  ^probability  that  there  are  no  Honours 

on  either  ride  is  ^c '  ^^^  of  course  means  that  the  Honours 

are  equally  divided.     The  result  would  be  obtained  by  considering 
two  cases,  namely,   1st,  that  in  which  the  card  turned  up  is  an 


DE  MOIVRE.  165 

Honour,  and   2nd,  that  in  which  the  card  turned  up  is  not  an 
Honour.     Thus  we  should  have  for  the  required  probability 

_4     8    25  .  26  .  25       9^    4^    25  .  24  .  26  .  25  ^ 
13  ■  T  *  51750 .  49  "*"  13  *  1 .  2  '  51 .  50 .  49  .  48  ^ 

and  this  will  be  found  equal  to      -^^  . 

loob 

De  Moivi'e  has  two  Corollaries,  which  form  the  chief  part  of 
his  investigation  respecting  Whist. 
The  first  begins  thus : 

From  what  we  have  said,  it  will  not  be  difficult  to  solve  this  Case 
at  Whisk;  viz.  which  side  has  the  best,  of  those  who  have  viii  of 
the  Game,  or  of  those  who  at  the  same  time  have  ix? 

In  order  to  which  it  will  be  necessary  to  premise  the  following 
Principle. 

1°  That  there  is  but  1  Chance  in  8192  to  get  vii.  by  Triks. 

2°  That  there  are  13  Chances  in  8192  to  get  vi. 

3"  That  there  are  78  Chances  in  8192  to  get  v. 

4"  That  there  are  286  Chances  in  8192  to  get  iv. 

5°  That  there  are  715  Chances  in  8192  to  get  iii. 

6°  That  there  are  1287  Chances  in  8192  to  get  n. 

7"  That  there  are  1716  Chances  in  8192  to  get  i. 

All  this  will  appear  evident  to  those  who  can  raise  the  Binomial 
a  +  b  to  its  thirteenth  power. 

But  it  must  carefully  be  observed  that  the  foregoing  Chances  ex- 
press the  Probability  of  getting  so  many  Points  by  Triks,  and  neither 
more  nor  less. 

De  Moivre  states  his  conclusion  thus  : 

From  whence  it  follows  that  without  considering  whether  the  viii 
are  Dealers  or  Eldest,  there  is  one  time  with  another  the  Odds  of 
somewhat  less  than  7  to  5;  and  very  nearly  that  of  25  to  18. 

The  second  Corollary  contains  tables  of  the  number  of  chances 
for  any  assigned  number  of  Trumps  in  any  hand.     De  Moivre  says, 

By  the  help  of  these  Tables  several  useful  Questions  may  be  re- 
solved; as  1°.  If  it  is  asked,  what  is  the  Probability  that  the  Dealer 
has  precisely   iii  Trumps,    besides  the  Trump   Card  ]       The   Answer, 

.      rp  .        .      4662 
by  Tab.  i.  is    .^^^^  ;   ... 
158y5 


166  DE  MOIVRE. 

In  tlie  first  edition  there  was  only  a  brief  notice  of  Whist, 
occupying  scarcely  more  than  a  page. 

299.  Problems  LI.  to  LV.  are  on  Piquet.  The  game  is  not 
described,  but  there  is  no  difficulty  in  understanding  the  problems, 
which  are  easy  examples  of  combinations.  The  following  Remark 
occurs  on  page  186 ;  it  was  not  in  the  first  edition  : 

It  may  easily  be  perceived  from  tlie  Solution  of  the  preceding 
Problem,  that  the  number  of  variations  which  there  are  in  twelve 
Cards  make  it  next  to  impossible  to  calculate  some  of  the  Probabili- 
ties relating  to  Piquet,  such  as  that  which  results  from  the  priority 
of  Hand,  or  the  Probabilities  of  a  Pic,  Kepic  or  Lurch  j  however  not- 
withstanding that  difficulty,  one  may  from  observations  often  repeated, 
nearly  estimate  what  those  Probabilities  are  in  themselves,  as  will  be 
proved  in  its  place  when  we  come  to  treat  of  the  reasonable  conjec- 
tures which  may  be  deduced  from  Experiments;  for  which  reason  I 
shall  set  down  some  Observations  of  a  Gentleman  who  has  a  very  great 
degree  of  Skill  and  Experience  in  that  Game,  after  which  I  shall  make 
an  application  of  them. 

The  discussion  of  Piquet  was  briefer  in  the  first  than  in  the 
followinof  editions.  . 


"O 


•300.  We  will  give  the  enunciation  of  Problem  LVI.  and  the 
beginning  of  the  solution. 

Problem  LVI.     Of  Saving  Clauses. 

A  has  2  Chances  to  beat  B^  and  B  has  1  chance  to  beat  A  ;  but 
there  is  one  Chance  which  intitlcs  them  both  to  withdraw  their  own 
Stake,  which  we  suppose  equal  to  s  j  to  find  the  Gain  of  A. 

Solution. 

This  Question  tho'  easy  in  itself,  yet  is  brought  in  to  caution  Be- 
ginners against  a  Mistake  which  they  might  commit  by  imagining 
that  the  Case,  which  intitles  each  Man  to  recover  his  own  Stake,  needs 
not  be  regarded,  and  that  it  is  the  same  thing  as  if  it  did  not  exist. 
This  I  mention  so  much  more  readily,  that  some  people  who  have 
pretended  gi-eat  skill  in  these  Speculations  of  Chance  have  themselves 
fallen  into  that  error. 


DE  MOIVRE.  1G7 

This  problem  was  not  in  the   first  edition.      The  gain  of  A 

.     1 

IS   75. 

301.  Problem  LVir,  which  was  not  in  the  first  edition,  is  as 
follows : 

A  and  B  playing  together  deposit  £s  apiece ;  A  lias  2  Chances  to 
win  s,  and  B  1  Chance  to  win  5,  whereupon  A  tells  B  that  he  will 
play  with  him.  upon  an  equality  of  Chance,  if  he  B  will  set  him  2s  to  I5, 
to  which  B  assents :  to  find  whether  A  has  any  advantage  or  disad- 
vantage by  that  Bargain. 

In  the  first  case  ^'s  expectation  is  -  s,  and  in  the   second, 

o 

it  is  ^  5 ;  so  that  he  gains  ^  s  by  the  bargain. 

802.  We  now  arrive  at  one  of  the  most  important  parts  of 
De  Moivre's  work,  namely,  that  which  relates  to  the  Duration  of 
Play ;  we  will  first  give  a  full  account  of  what  is  contained  in  the 
third  edition  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances,  and  afterwards  state  how 
much  of  this  was  added  to  the  investigations  originally  published 
in  the  De  Mensura  Sortis. 

De  Moivre  himself  regarded  his  labours  on  this  subject  with 
the  satisfaction  which  they  justly  merited ;  he  says  in  his 
Preface, 

When  I  first  began  to  attempt  the  general  Solution  of  the  Problem 
concerning  the  Duration  of  Play,  there  was  nothing  extant  that  could 
give  me  any  light  into  that  Subject;  for  altho'  Mr  de  Monmort^  in  the 
first  Edition  of  his  Book,  gives  the  Solution  of  this  Problem,  as  limited 
to  three  Stakes  to  be  won  or  lost,  and  farther  limited  by  the  Suppo- 
sition of  an  Equality  of  Skill  between  the  Adventurers;  yet  he  having 
given  no  Demonstration  of  his  Solution,  and  the  Demonstration  when 
discovered  being  of  very  little  use  towards  obtaining  the  general  Solu- 
tion of  the  Problem,  I  was  forced  to  try  what  my  own  Enquiry  would 
lead  me  to,  which  having  been  attended  with  Success,  the  result  of 
what  I  found  was  afterwards  published  in  my  Specimen  before  men- 
tioned. 

The  Specimen  is  the  Essay  De  Mensura  Sortis. 


168  DE  MOIVRE. 

803.  The  general  problem  relating  to  the  Duration  of  Play 
may  be  thus  enunciated :  suppose  A  to  have  m  counters,  and  B 
to  have  n  counters  ;  let  their  chances  of  winning  in  a  single  game 
be  as  a  to  Z> ;  the  loser  in  each  game  is  to  give  a  counter  to  his 
adversary  :  required  the  probability  tliat  when  or  before  a  certain 
number  of  games  has  been  played,  one  of  the  players  will  have  won 
all  the  counters  of  his  adversary.  It  will  be  seen  that  the  words 
in  italics  constitute  the  advance  whi'ch  this  problem  makes  beyond 
the  more  simple  one  discussed  in  Art.  107. 

De  Moivre's  Problems  LVIII.  and  Lix.  amount  to  solving  the 
problem  of  the  Duration  of  Play  for  the  case  in  which  m  and  n 
are  equal. 

After  discussing  some  cases  in  which  n  =  2  or  3,  De  Moivi*e 
lays  down  a  General  Rule,  thus : 

A  General  Rule  for  determining  what  Probability  there  is  that 
the  Play  shall  not  be  determined  in  a  given  number  of  Games. 

Let  71  be  the  number  of  Pieces  of  each  Gamester.  Let  also  n-hd 
be  the  number  of  Games  given;  raise  a  +  h  to  the  Power  n,  then  cut  off 
the  two  extream  Terms,  and  multiply  the  remainder  by  aa  +  2ab  +  hb  : 
then  cut  off  again  the  two  Extreams,  and  multiply  again  the  remaiiM^er 
by  aa  +  2ab  +  hb,  still  rejecting  the  two  Extreams;  and  so  on,  makiog 

as  many  Multiplications  as  there  are  Units  in  ^d ;  make  the  last  Pro- 

duct  the  Numerator  of  a  Fraction  whose  Denominator  let  be  (a  +  b)"'^'\ 
and  that  Fraction  will  express  tlie  Probalnlity  required, ;  still  ob- 
serving that  if  d  be  an  odd  number,  you  wj-ite  d—1  in  its  room. 

For  an  example,  De  Moivre  supposes  n  =  4<,  d=  6. 

Raise  a+h  to  the  fourth  power,  and  reject  the  extremes ;  thus 
we  have  4<a^b  +  MV  +  ^a¥. 

Multiply  by  a^  +  2ab  +  V^,  and  reject  the  extremes ;  thus  we 
have  l^a'h'  +  2^a%'  +  Ua^h\ 

Multiply  by  <^  +  2ah  +  W,  and  reject  the  extremes ;  thus  we 
have  48a'Z>'  +  Q%a%'  +  ^Mh\ 

Multiply  by  a^+2«&  +  Z>^  and  reject  the  extremes;  thus  we 
have  lUa%'  +  232a'Z>'^  +  l(j^a'h\ 

Thus  the  probability  that  the  Play  will  not  be  ended  in 
10  games  is 


DE  MOIVRE.  169 


,10 


(a  +  by 

De  Moivre  leaves  his  readers  to  convince  themselves  of  the 
accuracy  of  his  rule  ;   and  this  is  not  difficult. 

De  Moivre  suggests  that  the  work  of  multiplication  may  be 
abbreviated  by  omitting  the  a  and  h,  and  restoring  them  at  the 
end ;  this  is  what  we  now  call  the  method  of  detached  coefficients. 

304.  The  terms  which  are  rejected  in  the  process  of  the 
preceding  Article  will  furnish  an  expression  for  the  probability 
that  the  play  ivill  be  ended  in  an  assigned  number  of  games. 
Thus  if  ?i  =  4  and  d  =  ^,  this  probability  will  be  found  to  be 

a'  +  b'       ^a'b  +  ^ab'      l^a%'' -\-\^a%'      48a^6^  +  48a^^>^ 
{a-^by^     {a  +  bf    "^        {a  +  hf       "^   .    {a-\-bf'      * 

Now  here  we  arrive  at  one  of  De  Moi\T:e's  important  results ; 
he  gives,  luithout  demonstj^ation,  general  formulae  for  determining 
those  numerical  coefficients  which  in  the  above  example  have  the 
values  4,  14,  48.  De  Moivre's  formulae  amount  to  two  laws,  one 
connecting  each  coefficient  with  its  predecessors,  and  one  giving 
the  value  of  each  coefficient  separately.  We  can  make  the  laws 
most  intelligible  by  demonstrating  them.  We  start  from  a  result 
given  by  Laplace.  He  shews,  Theorie . . .  des  Prob.,  page  229, 
that  the  chance  of  A  for  winning  precisely  at  the  (n  +  2x)*'*  game 
is  the  coefficient  of  T"^^  in  the  expansion  of 


( i  +  ^{i--^abf)  r     M  -  V(l  - -^abt')  r ' 

I  2  l^-j  2  J 

where  it  is  supposed  that  a  +  b  =  1. 

Now  the  denominator  of  the  above  expression  is  known  to  be 
equal  to 

^      1.2  [3  0  -t  ... 

where  c  =  abt^ ;  see  Differential  Calculus,  Chapter  ix. 


170  .  DE  MOIVRE. 

We  can  tlius  obtain  by  the  ordinary  doctrine  of  Series,  a  linear 
relation  between  the  coefficient  of  f^^""  and  the  coefficients  of  the 
preceding  powers  of  t,  namely,  r'^^^  ^""^^"^  ...  This  is  De 
Moivre's  first  law;  see  his  page  198. 

Again ;  we  may  wiite  the  above  fraction  in  the  form 

JV"  (1  +  c"iY"^") ' 

,                                               1  +  ^(1  _  4^ahe) 
where  N  = --^ ; 

2 

and  then  by  expanding,  we  obtain 

The  coefficient  of  f''  in  N'"  is  known  to  be 

^j^n  {n-{-.x-\-l)  {n  -{-x  +  2)  ...  {n  ■\-  2x  —  1)  ^ 

'  X  ' 


see  Differential  Calculus,  Chapter  ix. 

Similarly  we  get  the  coefficient  of  f^''  in  N-'\  of  i'^'*"  in 
iV"^**,  and  so  on. 

Thus  we  obtain  the  coefficient  of  f'"^^  in  the  expansion  of  the 
original  expression. 

This  is  De  Moivre's  second  law ;  see  his  page  199. 

805.  De  Moivre's  Problems  LX.  LXi.  LXii.  are  simple  ex- 
amples formed  on  Problems  LVIII.  and  Lix.  They  are  thus 
enunciated : 

LX.  Supposing  A  and  B  to  play  together  till  such  time  as  four 
Stakes  are  won  or  lost  on  either  side ;  what  must  be  their  proportion 
of  Skill,  otherwise  what  must  be  their  proportion  of  Chances  for  win- 
ning any  one  Game  assigned,  to  make  it  as  probable  that  the  Play  will 
be  ended  in  four  Games  as  not? 

LXI.  Supposing  that  A  and  B  play  till  such  time  as  four  Stakes 
are  won  or  lost :  What  must  be  their  proportion  of  Skill  to  make  it  a 
Wager  of  three  to  one,  that  the  Play  will  be  ended  in  four  Games  % 

LXII.  Su2:>posing  that  A  and  B  play  till  such  time  as  four  Stakes 
are  won  or  lost ;  What  must  be  their  proportion  of  Skill  to  make  it  an 
equal  Wager  that  the  Play  will  be  ended  in  six  Games  ? 


DE  MOIVRE.  171 

806.  Problems  LXiii.  and  LXiv.  amount  to  the  general  enun- 
ciation we  have  given  in  Art.  303 ;  so  that  the  restriction  that 
m  and  n  are  equal  which  was  imposed  in  Problems  LVIII.  and 
Lix.  is  now  removed.  As  before  De  Moivre  states,  tuithout  de- 
monstration, two  general  laws,  which  we  will  now  give. 

Laplace  shews,  T]ieorie...des  Prob.  page  228,  that  the  chance 
of  A  for  winning  precisely  at  the  {n  +  2u?)*'^  game  is  the  coefficient 
of  f^'^'^  in  the  expansion  of 

f  1  +  V(l  -  4c)  ) "      f  1  -  V(l  -  4c)  1  "^ 


r-{ 


m 


1  9  9 

j  1  +  ^(1  _  4c)  r"^'^     ( 1  -  v(i  -  4c)  I '"^'*  • 


Let  s) —   ^^  denoted  by  h  \  then  the  fractional  expression 

which  multiplies  a"^*"  becomes  by  expansion,  and  striking  out  2h 
from  numerator  and  denominator, 

ay^-'     m{m-V){m-2)  /1\'""%2    w(772-l)(w-2)(m-3)(m-4)  [ly^, 

.       ^lY"--^"-^  ,  (m+^2)(m+^^-l)(m+?i-2)  /l^""^"-",,  , 
(^+^)(2J         + g %)         ^^+- 

We  have  to  arrange  the  denominator  according  to  powers  of 
t,  and  to  shew  that  it  is  equal  to 

where  7  =  m  +  n  —  2. 

Now,  as  in  Art.  30-A,  we  have 


{ 


1  +  V(l  -  4c)  I"  ^  1 1  -  V(l  -  4c)  r 


=  l_,e  +  '-(p^8)^,_r(,-4)(r-o)^3_^   __. 
and  the  left-hand  member  is  equivalent  to 


172  DE   MOIVRE. 

Differentiate  both  sides  with  respect  to  t  observing  that 

Mh 

——-=:^aot.     inns, 
dt 

^  2  {  r  -  '-^^  aU  +  '  ^'  -f  ^^  -  ^^  (abtr  -... 

Now  put  r  =  Z  +  3  ;  and  we  obtain  the  required  result. 
Thus  a  linear  relation  can  be  obtained  between  the  coefficients 
of  successive  powers  of  t. 

This  is  De  Moivre's  first  law ;  see  his  page  205. 

1  _l_  a/(1  —  4c) 
Again  ;   let  iV= ^ ~  ;   then  the   original  expression 

becomes 

'\Jni+n  /-|  m+n  7vr-2wt-2n\ 

=  d'fN-''  (1  -  c'"iV^"'"0  (1  -  c"*^"^-'"^-'")"'- 
We  may  now  proceed  as  in  the  latter  part  of  Art.  304,  to  de- 
termine the  coefficient  of  r"*"^"". 

The  result  will  coincide  with  De  Moivre's  second  law ;  see  his 
page  207. 

307.  Problem  LXV.  is  a  particular  case  of  the  problem  of 
Duration  of  Play ;  m  is  now  supposed  infinite  :  in  other  words 
A  has  unlimited  cajntal  and  we  require  his  chance  of  ruining  B  in 
an  assigned  number  of  games. 

De  Moivre  solves  this  problem  in  two  ways.  We  will  here 
give  his  first  solution  with  the  first  of  the  two  examples  which  ac- 
company it. 

Solution. 

Supposing  n  to  be  the  number  of  Stakes  which  A  is  to  win  of  B^ 
and  n  +  d  the  number  of  Games ;  let  on-  6  be  raised  to  the  Power  whose 
Index  is  7i  +  d;  then  if  d  be  an   odd  number,   take  so  many  Terms  of 

that  Power  as  there  are  Units  in  — ^ — j    take  also  so  many  of  the 

Terms  next  following  as  have  been  taken  already,  but  prefix  to  them 
in  an  inverted  oi^der,  the  Coefficients  of  the  preceding  Terms.  But  if 
d  be  an  even  number,  take  so  many  Terms  of  the  said  Power  as  there 


DE  MOIVRE.  173 

are  Units  in-d+l;  then  take  as  many  of  tlie  Terms  next  following 

as  there  are  Units  in  ^  d,  and  prefix  to  them  in  an  inverted  order  the 

Coefiicients  of  the  preceding  Terms,  omitting  the  last  of  them;  and 
those  Terms  taken  all  together  will  compose  the  Numerator  of  a  Frac- 
tion expressing  the  Probability  required,  the  Denominator  of  which 
Fraction  ought  to  be  {a  +  S)"^**. 

Example  I. 

Supposing  the  number  of  Stakes,  which  A  is  to  win,  to  be  Three, 
and  the  given  number  of  Games  to  be  Ten;  let  a+h  be  raised  to  the 
tenth  power,  viz.  a'' +  lOa'h  +  ioa'bh  +  UOa' b' +  210a'b'  +  252a'b' 
+  210a'' 6'  +  120a' 6'  +  45aa&'  +  lOab'  +  b'".     Then,  by  reason  that  n^3, 

and  w  + 6^=10,  it  follows  that  d  is  =7,  and    — ^r— =  4.     Wherefore  let 

Z 

the  Four  first  Terms  of  the  said  Power  be  taken,  viz.  a^°  +  lOa^b 
+  4:5a^bb  +  120a''b^,  and  let  the  four  Terms  next  following  be  taken 
likewise  without  regard  to  their  Coefficients,  then  prefix  to  them  in  an 
inverted  order,  the  Coefficients  of  the  preceding  Terms  :  thus  the  four 
Terms  following  with  their  new  Coefficients  will  be  120a^b^  +  4:5a^b^ 
+  10a^b^+la^b^.  Then  the  Probability  which  ^  has  of  winning  three 
Stakes  of  £  in  ten  Games  or  sooner,  will  be  expressed  by  the  following 
Fraction 

a'o  ^  iQ^,9  J  ^  45^8^5  ^  UOa'b^  +  UOa'b'  +  iSa'b'  +  lOa'b'  +  a'b' 

'  {a  +  by  ' 

which  in  the   Case  of  an  Equality  of  Skill  between  A  and  B  will  be 

A       w      352  11 

reducea  to  r— --r-  or  ^r^ . 
1024        32 

808.  In  De  Moivre's  solution  there  is  no  difficulty  in  seeing 
the  origin  of  his  fii'st  set  of  terms,  but  that  of  the  second  set  of 
terms  is  not  so  immediately  obvious.  We  will  take  his  example, 
and  account  for  the  last  four  terms. 

The  last  term  is  a^b\  There  is  only  one  way  in  which  ^'s 
capital  may  be  exhausted  while  A  wins  only  three  games  ;  namely, 
A  must  win  the  first  three  games. 

The  next  term  is  10a'b\  There  are  ten  ways  in  which  B's 
capital  may  be  exhausted  while  A  wins  only  four  games.  For  let 
there  be  ten  places ;  put  h  in  any  one  of  the  first  three  places, 


17-i  BE  MOIVKE. 

and  fill  up  the  remaining  places  with  the  letters  aaaahlhhh  in  this 
order  ;-  or  put  a  in  any  one  of  the  last  seven  places,  and  fill  up  the 
remaining  places  with  the  letters  aaahbhhhh  in  this  order  ;  we  thus 
obtain  the  ten  admissible  cases. 

The  next  term  is  4t5a%^.  There  are  forty -five  ways  in  which 
i?'s  capital  may  be  exhausted  while  A  wins  only  five  games. 
For  let  there  be  ten  places.  Take  any  two  of  the  first  three 
places  and  put  h  in  each,  and  fill  up  the  remaining  places  with 
the  letters  aaaaabhh  in  this  order.  Or  take  any  two  of  the 
last  seven  places  and  put  a  in  each,  and  fill  up  the  remaining 
places  with  the  letters  aaahhhhh  in  this  order.  Or  put  h  in  any 
one  of  the  first  three  places  and  a  in  any  one  of  the  last  seven ; 
and  fill  up  the  remaining  places  with  the  letters  aaaabhhh  in  this 
order.  On  the  whole  we  shall  obtain  a  number  equal  to  the  num- 
ber of  combinations  of  10  things  taken  2  at  a  time.  The  following 
is  the  general  result :  suppose  we  have  to  arrange  r  letters  a  and 
s  letters  h,  so  that  in  each  arrangement  there  shall  be  n  more 
of  the  letters  a  than  of  the  letters  h  before  we  have  gone  through 
the  arrangement ;  then  if  r  is  less  than  s  +  n  the  number  of 
different  arrangements  is  the  same  as  the  number  of  combina- 
tions of  T  -\-s  things  taken  r  —  w  at  a  time.  For  example,  let 
r  =  6,  s  =  4,  w  =  3 ;  then  the  number  of  different  arrangements  is 

10  X  9  X  8     ,,    ,  .    ^^_ 

— — rr  .  that  IS  120. 

1x2x3 

The  result  which  we  have  here  noticed  was  obtained  by  Mont- 
mort,  but  in  a  very  unsatisfactory  manner :  see  Art.  182. 

De  Moivre's  first  solution  of  his  Problem  LXV.  is  based  on  the 
same  principles  as  Montmort's  solution  of  the  general  problem 
of  the  Duration  of  Play. 

809.  De  Moivre's  second  solution  of  his  Problem  LXV.  con- 
sists of  a  formula  which  he  gives  without  demonstration.  Let  us 
return  to  the  expression  in  Ai't.  306,  and  suppose  m  infinite.  Then 
the  chance  of  A  for  winning  precisely  at  the  (n  +  2ic)*''  game  is 
the  coefficient  of  f^^""  in  the  expansion  of 

(l  +  V(i-4c) 


n   > 


DE  MOIVRE,  175 

that  IS      a  -^ — \ — ^^ a^  ; 

[x  ' 

see  Art..  804. 

The  chance  of  A  for  winning  at  or  he/ore  the  (n  -f  2^)*^'  game 
is  therefore 


a-  I  l+nah  +  '-^^-^^^  a'lf -\-  ... 


niii^-x  +  1)  (?i  +  a?  +  2)  ...  {7i^2x-l)    ,-,, 
+  — ^ ^^ ^ ^^ -'  ah 

\x 

Laplace,  T]ieorie...des  Proh.,  page  235. 

310.  De  Moivre  says  with  respect  to  his  Problem  LXV, 

In  the  first  attempt  that  I  had  ever  made  towards  solving  tlie 
general  Problem  of  the  Duration  of  Play,  which  was  in  the  year  1708, 
I  began  with  the  Solution  of  this  lxv^^  Problem,  well  knowing  that 
it  might  be  a  Foundation  for  what  I  farther  wanted,  since  which  time, 
by  a  due  repetition  of  it,  I  solved  the  main  Problem :  but  as  I  found 
afterwards  a  nearer  way  to  it,  I  barely  published  in  my  first  Essay  on 
those  mattei'S,  what  seemed  to  me  most  simple  and  elegant,  still  pre- 
serving this  Problem  by  me  in  order  to  be  published  when  I  should 
think  it  proper. 

De  Moivre  goes  on  to  speak  of  the  investigations  of  Montmort 
and  Nicolas  Bernoulli,  in  words  which  we  have  akeady  quoted  ;  see 
Art.  181. 

311.  Dr  L.  Oettinger  on  pages  187,  188  of  his  work  entitled 
Die  Wahrscheinlichkeits-Rechnung,  Berlin,  1852,  objects  to  some 
of  the  results  which  are  obtained  by  De  Moivre  and  Laplace. 

Dr  Oettinger  seems  to  intimate  that  in  the  formula,  which  we 
have  given  at  the  end  of  Art.  309,  Laplace  has  omitted  to  lay 
down  the  condition  that  A  has  an  unlimited  capital ;  but  Laplace 
has  distinctly  introduced  this  condition  on  his  page  234. 

Again,  speaking  of  De  Moivre's  solution  of  his  Problem  LXiv. 
Dr  Oettinger  says,  Er  erhiilt  das  namliche  unhaltbare  Resultat, 
welches  Laplace  nach  ihm  aufstellte. 

But  there  is  no  foundation  for  this  remark  ;  De  Moivre  and 


176  DE  MOIVRE. 

Laplace  are  correct.  The  misapprehension  may  have  arisen  from 
reading  only  a  part  of  De  Moivre's  page  205,  and  so  assuming  a 
law  of  a  series  to  hold  universally,  which  he  distinctly  says  breaks 
off  after  a  certain  number  of  terms. 

The  just  reputation  of  Dr  Oettinger  renders  it  necessary  for  me 
to  notice  his  criticisms,  and  to  record  my  dissent  from  them. 

812.  De  Moivre's  Problems  Lxvi.  and  LXVii.  are  easy  deduc- 
tions from  his  preceding  results  ;  they  are  thus  enunciated  : 

LXVI.  To  find  what  Probability  there  is  that  in  a  given  number 
of  Games  A  may  be  a  winner  of  a  certain  number  q  of  Stakes,  and  at 
some  other  time  B  may  likewise  be  winner  of  the  number  p  of  Stakes, 
so  that  both  circumstances  may  happen. 

LXVII.  To  find  what  Probability  there  is,  that  in  a  given  number 
of  Games  A  may  win  the  number  q  of  Stakes ;  with  this  farther  con- 
dition, that  £  during  that  whole  number  of  Games  may  never  have 
been  winner  of  the  number  j^  of  Stakes. 

813.  De  Moivre  now  proceeds  to  express  his  results  relating 
to  the  Duration  of  Play  in  another  form.     He  says,  page  215, 

The  Pules  hitherto  given  for  the  Solution  of  Problems  relating  to 
the  Duration  of  Play  are  easily  practicable,  if  the  number  of  Games 
given  is  but  small ;  but  if  that  number  is  large,  the  work  will  be  very 
tedious,  and  sometimes  swell  to  that  degree  as  to  be  in  some  manner 
impracticable  :  to  remedy  which  inconveniency,  I  shall  here  give  an 
Extract  of  a  paper  by  me  produced  before  the  Poyal  Society,  wherein 
was  contained  a  Method  of  solving  very  expeditiously  the  chief  Pro- 
blems relating  to  that  matter,  by  the  help  of  a  Table  of  Sines,  of  which 
I  had  before  given  a  hint  in  the  first  Edition  of  my  Doctrine  of  Chances, 
pag.  149,  and  150. 

The  paper  produced  before  the  Poyal  Society  does  not  appear 
to  have  been  published  in  the  Philosophical  Transactions;  pro- 
bably we  have  the  substance  of  it  in  the  Docty^ine  of  Chances. 

De  Moivre  proceeds  according  to  the  announcement  in  the 
above  extract,  to  express  his  results  relating  to  the  Duration  of 
Play  by  the  help  of  Trigonometrical  Tables;  in  Problem  LXVIII.  he 
supposes  the  players  to  have  equal  skill,  and  in  Problem  LXix.  he 
supposes  them  to  have  unequal  skill. 


DE   MOIYRE.  177 

The  demonstrations  of  the  formulae  are  to  be  found  in  the  Mis- 
cellanea Analytica,  pages  76 — 83,  and  in  the  Doctrine  of  Chances, 
pages  230 — 234.  De  Moivre  supposes  the  players  to  start  with  the 
same  number  of  counters ;  but  he  says  on  page  83  of  the  Miscel- 
lanea Analytica,  that  solutions  similar  but  somewhat  more  complex 
could  be  given  for  the  case  in  which  the  original  numbers  of 
counters  were  different.  This  has  been  effected  by  Laplace  in  his 
discussion  of  the  whole  problem. 

314.  De  Moivre's  own  demonstrations  depend  on  his  doctrine 
of  Recurring  Series  ;  by  this  doctrine  De  Moivre  could  effect  what 
we  should  now  call  the  integration  of  a  linear  equation  in  Finite 
Differences  :  the  equation  in  this  case  is  that  furnished  by  the  first 
of  the  two  laws  which  we  have  explained  in  Arts.  304,  306.  Cer- 
tain trigonometrical  formulae  are  also  required ;  see  Miscellanea 
Analytica,  page  78.  One  of  these,  De  Moivre  says,  constat  ex 
-^quationibus  ad  circulum  vulgo  notis  ;  the  following  is  the  pro- 
perty :  in  elementary  works  on  Trigonometry  we  have  an  expan- 
sion of  cos  7x6  in  descending  powers  of  cos  6 ;  now  cos  nO  vanishes 

when  nO  is  any  odd  multiple  of  -^  ,  and  therefore  the  equivalent  ex- 

pansion  must  also  vanish.  The  other  formulae  which  De  Moivre 
uses  are  in  fact  deductions  from  the  general  theorem  which  is 
called  De  Moivre's  property  of  the  Circle;   they  are  as  follows ; 

TT 

let  a  =  ^7- ,  then  we  have 
2?i 

1  =  2""^  sin  a  sin  3a  sin  5a  ...  sin  (2/ia  —  a)  ; 

also  if  n  be  even  we  have 

cos  n(^  =  2""^  [sin^  a  —  sin^  </>}  {sin^  3a  —  sin^  0} . . . 

. . .  { sin^  {n  —  3)  a  —  sin^  <^}  { sin^  (ti  —  1)  a  —  sin^  0}  : 

see  Plane  Trigonometry,  Chap,  xxiii. 

De  Moivre  uses  the  first  of  these  formulae  ;  and  also  a  formula 
which  may  be  deduced  from  the  second  by  differentiating  with 
respect  to  (f),  and  after  differentiation  putting  </>  equal  to  a,  or 
3a,  or  5a, ... 

315.  De  Moivre  applies  his  results  respecting  the  Duration 

12 


178  DE   MOIVRE. 

of  Play  to  test  the  value  of  an  approximation  proposed  by  Mont- 
mort ;  we  have  already  referred  to  this  point  in  Art.  184. 

316.  It  remains  to  trace  the  history  of  De  Moivre's  investi- 
gations on  this  subject. 

The  memoir  De  Mensura  Sortis  contains  the  following  Pro- 
blems out  of  those  which  appear  in  the  Doctrine  of  Chances, 
LVIII,  LX,  LXII,  LXIII,  the  first  solution  of  LXV,  LXVI.  The  first 
edition  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances  contains  all  that  the  third  does, 
except  the  Problems  LXVIII.  and  LXix ;  these  were  added  in  the 
second  edition.  As  we  proceed  with  our  history  we  shall  find 
that  the  subject  engaged  the  attention  of  Lagrange  and  Laplace, 
the  latter  of  whom  has  embodied  the  researches  of  his  prede- 
cessors in  the  Theorie...des  Proh.  pages  225 — 238. 

317.  With  one  slight  exception  noticed  in  Art.  322,  the  re- 
mainder of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances  was  not  in  the  first  edition  but 
was  added  in  the  second  edition. 

318.  The  pages  220 — 229  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances,  form 
a  digression  on  a  subject,  which  is  one  of  De  Moivre's  most 
valuable  contributions  to  mathematics,  namely  that  of  Recurring 
Series.     He  says,  page  220, 

The  E-eader  may  have  perceived  that  the  Sohition  of  several  Pro- 
blems relating  to  Chance  depends  upon  the  Summation  of  Series;  I 
have,  as  occasion  has  offered,  given  the  Method  of  summing  them  up; 
but  as  there  are  others  that  may  occur,  I  think  it  necessary  to  give 
a  summary  Yiew  of  what  is  most  requisite  to  be  known  in  this  matter; 
desiring  the  Reader  to  excuse  me,  if  I  do  not  give  the  Demonstrations, 
which  would  swell  this  Tract  too  much;  especially  considering  that  I 
have  already  given  them  in  my  Miscellanea  Analytica. 

319.  These  pages  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances  will  not  present 
any  difficulty  to  a  student  who  is  acquainted  with  the  subject  of 
Recurring  Series,  as  it  is  now  explained  in  works  on  Algebra ; 
De  Moivre  however  gives  some  propositions  which  are  not  usually 
reproduced  in  the  present  day. 

320.  One  theorem  may  be  noticed  which  is  enunciated  by 
De  Moivre,  on  his  page  224,  and  also  on  page  167  of  the  Miscellanea 
Analytica. 


DE   MOIYUE.  179 

The  general  term  of  the   expansion  of  (1  —  r)~^  in  powers  of 

r  is  ^-^ '" r^ ;    the  sum  of  the  first  n  terms  of 

the  expansion  is  equivalent  to  the  following  expression 

^        ^  1.2         ^        ^  n—\  i^J— 1 


(l-r)" 

This  may  be  easily  shewn  to  be  true  when  n=  1,  and  then, 
by  induction,  it  may  be  shewn  to  be  generally  true.     For 

r«+i  =  r"|l-(l-r)}, 
so  that 

r-^^  +  (^  +  1)  r"^^  (1  -  r)  +  ^''  "^  ^  ^l  "^  ^^  r""^^  (1  _  r)^  +  . . . 
=  r«  |l  _  (1  _,.)}  +(«+!)  r»  (1  - r)  |l  -  (1  - r)} 

n{n-\-V\  \n  +  p—  2 

=  ^"  +  ^^"  (1  -r)  +  ""^V    ^'"  (1  -0'+  •  •  •  +    ^ Ti 1  ''"  (1  -  ^')' 

^        ^  l.z         ^        ^  ?i  —  Iw  —  1  ^ 


P 


^ ,.« (1  _  ^)p. 


\n\j)  —  1 


Thus  the  additional  term  obtained  by  changing  oi  into  n  +  1 

\n  -\-p—  1 

is    I  — , r-  r"  as  it  should  be ;  so  that  if  De  Moivre's  theorem  is 

\np—\.  ' 


true  for  any  value  of  ?2,  it  is  true  when  n  is  changed  into  ii-\-l. 

321.  Another  theorem  may  be  noticed  ;  it  is  enunciated  by 
De  Moivre  on  his  page  229.  Having  given  the  scales  of  relation 
of  two  Recurring  Series,  it  is  required  to  find  the  scale  of  relation 
of  the  Series  arising  from  the  product  of  corresponding  terms. 

For  example,  let  w^^r"  be  the  general  term  in  the  expansion 
according  to  powers  of  r  of  a  proper  Algebraical  fraction  of  which 
the  denominator  is  1  —fr  4-  gr'^ ;  and  let  t'„a"  be  the  general  term 
in  the  expansion  according  to  powers  of  a  of  a  proper  Algebraical 

12—2 


180  I>E  MOIVRE. 

fraction  of  which   the   denominator   is    1  -  ma  +  pa^.     We   have 
to  find  the  scale  of  relation  of  the  Series  of  which  the  general 

term  is  u^Vn  {ro)'\ 

We  know  by  the  ordinary  theory  of  decomposing  Recurring 
Series  into  Geometrical  Progressions  that 

where  p^  and  p^  are  the  reciprocals  of  the  roots  of  the  equation 

and  a^  and  a^  are  the  reciprocals  of  the  roots  of  the  equation 

1  —ina  -\-pa^  =  0  ; 

and  R^,  R^,  A^,  A^  are  certain  constants. 

Thus  u^v^  =  R^A^  (p/^X  +  ^1^2  {pi^:T 

this  shews  that  the  required  scale  of  relation  will  involve  four 
terms  besides  unity.  The  four  quantities  p^a^,  p^a^,  p^a^,  p^7^  will 
be  the  reciprocals  of  the  roots  of  the  equation  in  z  which  is  found 
by  eliminating  r  and  a  from 

1  —fr  +  gr"^  =  0,     1  —  ma  +  pa^  =  0,     ra  —  z\ 

this  equation  therefore  is 

1  -fmz  +  {pP  +  gm^  —  2^p)  z^  —fgmjpz^  -^-g^fz^  —  0. 

Thus  we  have  determined  the  required  scale  of  relation ;  for 
the  denominator  of  the  fraction  which  by  expansion  produces 
w„t;„  (ra)"  as  its  general  term  will  be 

1  —fmra  +  {pf^+gm^  —  ^gjp)  ^V  —  fgmj^r^d  ■\- g^j^r^a^. 

De  Moivre  adds,  page  229, 

But  it  is  very  observable,  that  if  one  of  the  differential  Scales  be  the 
Binomial  \  —  a  raised  to  any  Power,  it  will  be  sufficient  to  raise  the  other 
differential  Scale  to  that  Power,  only  substituting  ar  for  ?•,  or  leaving 
the  Powers  of  r  as  they  are,  if  a  be  restrained  to  Unity;  and  that 
Power  of  the  other  differential  Scale  will  constitute  the  differential 
Scale  required. 


DE   MOIVEE.  181 

This  is  very  easily  demonstrated.  For  suppose  that  one  scale 
of  relation  is  (1  —  of ;  then  by  forming  the  ]3roduct  of  the  cor- 
responding terms  of  the  two  Recurring  Series,  we  obtain  for  the 
general  term 

===  a"  {Rj>:  +  E,p:  +  B,p:  +...] 


\n 


Tliis  shews  that  the  general  term  will  be  the  coefficient  of 
r"  in  the  expansion  of 

(l-rapy      {1-rap;)'      (1  -  rap^y      '" ' 

and  by  bringing  these  fractions  to  a  common  denominator,  we 
obtain  De  Moivre's  result. 

822.  De  Moivre  applies  his  theory  of  Recurring  Series  to 
demonstrate  his  results  relating  to  the  Duration  of  Play,  as  we 
have  already  intimated  in  Art.  313 ;  and  to  illustrate  still  further 
the  use  of  the  theory  he  takes  two  other  problems  respecting  j)lay. 
These  problems  are  thus  enunciated  : 

Lxx.  M  and  N,  whose  proportion  of  Chances  to  win  one  Game 
are  respectively  as  a  to  h,  resolve  to  play  together  till  one  or  the  other 
has  lost  4  Stakes:  two  Standers  by,  j5  and  S,  concern  themselves  in  the 
Play,  R  takes  the  side  of  M,  and  S  of  N,  and  agree  betwixt  them,  that  R 
shall  set  to  S,  the  sum  L  to  the  sum  G  on  the  first  Game,  2L  to  '2G  on 
the  second,  3Z  to  ?>G  on  the  third,  4Z  to  AG  on  the  fourth,  and  in  case 
the  Play  be  not  then  concluded,  5L  to  5G  on  the  fifth,  and  so  increasing 
perpetually  in  Arithmetic  Progression  the  Sums  which  they  are  to  set 
to  one  another,  as  long  as  M  and  iV  play;  yet  with  this  farther  con- 
dition, that  the  Sums,  set  down  by  them  R  and  aS',  shall  at  the  end  of 
each  Game  be  taken  up  by  the  Winner,  and  not  left  upon  the  Table  to 
be  taken  up  at  once  upon  the  Conclusion  of  the  Play:  it  is  demanded 
how  the  Gain  of  R  is  to  be  estimated  before  the  Play  begins. 

Lxxi.  If  M  and  iV,  whose  number  of  Chances  to  win  one  Game 
are  respectively  as  a  to  h,  play  together  till  four  Stakes  are  won  or  lost 
on  either  side ;  and  that  at  the  same  time,  R  and  S  whose  number  of 
Chances  to  win  one  Game  are  respectively  as  c  to  d,  play  also  together 
till  five  Stakes  are  won  or  lost  on  either  side ;  what  is  the  Probability 
that  the  Play  between  M  and  iV  will  be  ended  in  fewer  Games,  than  the 
Play  between  R  and  S. 


182  DE  MOIVKE. 

The  particular  case  of  Problem  LXXI,  in  which  a  =  h,  and 
c  =  d,  was  given  in  the  first  edition  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances, 
13age  152. 

823.  Problems  LXXII.  and  LXXIII.  are  important ;  it  will  be 
sufficient  to  enunciate  the  latter. 

A  and  B  playing  together,  and  having  a  different  number  of  Chances 
to  win  one  Game,  which  number  of  Chances  I  suppose  to  be  respectively 
as  a  to  h,  engage  themselves  to  a  Sj)ectator  S,  that  after  a  certain,  number 
of  Games  is  over,  A  shall  give  him  as  many  Pieces  as  he  wins  Games, 

over  and  above  ^  n,  and  B  as  many  as  he  wins  Games,  over  and  above 

the  number n ;   to  find  the  Expectation  of  S. 

Problem  LXXII.  is  a  particular  case  of  Problem  LXXIII.  obtained 
by  supposing  a  and  h  to  be  equal 

These  two  problems  first  appeared  in  the  Miscellanea  Ana- 
lytica,  pages  99 — 101.  We  there  find  the  following  notice  respect- 
ing Problem  LXXII : 

Cum  aliquando  labente  Anno  1721,  Yir  Clarissimus  Alex.  Cuming 
Eq.  Au.  Pegi?e  Societatis  Socius,  quaestionem  infra  subjectam  mihi 
proposuisset,  solutionem  problematis  ei  postero  die  tradideram. 

After  giving  the  solution  De  Moivre  proceeds  to  Problem  LXXIII. 
which  he  thus  introduces  : 

Eodem  procedendi  modo,  solutum  fuerat  Problema  sequens  ab  eodem 
CI.  viro  etiam  propositum,  ejusdem  generis  ac  superius  sed  multo  latins 
patens. 

We  will  give  a  solution  of  Problem  LXXIII ;  De  Moivre  in  the 
Doctrine  of  Chances  merely  states  the  result. 

Let  n  =  c  {a-\-h)  ',  consider  the   expectation  of  8  so  far  as  it 

depends  on  A.     The  chance  that  A  will  win  all  the   games  is 


a" 


ia  +  hy 


- ,  and  in  this  case  he  gives  ch  to  S.    The  chance  that  A  will 


.n-lj 


win  n—1  games  is  7 r-r  ,  and  in  this  case  he  gives  cl  —  l  to  S. 

And  so  on. 


DE   MOIVRE.  18.3 

Thus  we  have  to  sum  the  series 

a%c  +  ndr-'l  {he  -  1)  +  !?L^LdO  ^-252  (^c  -  2)  +  . . . , 

the  series  extending  so  long  as  the  terms  in  brackets  are  positive. 
"We  have 

a%c  -  noT-'h  =  a''~'h  (ac  -n)=-  aJ'-'b  he  ; 
thus  the  first  two  terms  amount  to 

{n-l)d;'''hhc. 

f2,  (fi  1^ 

Now  combine  this  with ^- — -~  a''~%^2  ;  we  ^et 

1.2  >         & 

(n  -  1)  a'^-'h'  (ac  -  7i),  that  is  -  (?i  -  1)  a'^-'h'hc  ; 

thus  the  first  tJu^ee  terms  amount  to 

1.2 

This  process  may  be  carried  on  for  any  number  of  terms  ;  and 
we  shall  thus  obtain  for  the  sum  of  he  terms 

(n-l)(n-2)       (n-ic  +  l)  ^,.-^,,...j^_ 
\oc  —  l 


This  may  be  expressed  thus 

[n 


n  I  he  I  ae 


a'^'h^'aehc, 


which  is  equivalent  to  De  Moivre's  result.     The  expectation  of  S 
from  B  will  be  found  to  be  the  same  as  it  is  from  A. 

82-i.  When  the  chances  of  A  and  B  for  winning  a  single  game 
are  in  the  proportion  of  a  to  &  we  know,  from  Bernoulli's  theorem, 
that  there  is  a  high  probability  that  in  a  large  number  of  trials  the 
number  of  games  won  by  A  and  B  respectively  will  be  nearly  in 
the  ratio  of  a  to  h.  Accordingly  De  Moivre  passes  naturally  from 
his  Problem  Lxxiii.  to  investigations  which  in  fact  amount  to  what 
we  have  called  the  inverse  use  of  Bernoulli's  theorem ;  see 
Art.  125.     De  Moivre  says, 


184  I>E  MOIVRE. 

...I'll  take  the  liberty  to  say,  tliat  tliis  is  tlie  hardest  Problem  that 
can  be  projDosed  on  the  Subject  of  Chance,  for  which  reason  I  have  re- 
served it  for  the  last,  but  I  hope  to  be  forgiven  if  my  Solution  is  not 
fitted  to  the  capacity  of  all  Headers;  however  I  shall  derive  from  it 
some  Conclusions  that  may  be  of  use  to  every  body :  in  order  thereto, 
I  shall  here  translate  a  Paper  of  mine  which  was  printed  November  12, 
1733,  and  communicated  to  some  Friends,  but  never  yet  made  public, 
reserving  to  myself  the  right  of  enlarging  my  own  Thoughts,  as  occasion 
shall  require. 

Then  follows  a  section  entitled  A  Method  of  a2yproximating  the 
Sum  of  the  Terms  of  the  Bmomial  (a  -1-  b)"  expanded  into  a  Series, 
from  lohence  are  deduced  some  practical  Rules  to  estimate  the 
Degree  of  Assent  which  is  to  he  given  to  Experiments.  This  section 
occupies  pages  243 — 254  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances;  we  shall  find 
it  convenient  to  postpone  our  notice  of  it  until  we  examine  the 
Miscellanea  Analytica. 

325.     De  Moivre's  Problem  LXXIV.  is  thus  enunciated : 

To  find  the  Probability  of  throwing  a    Chance    assigned   a   given 
'  number  of  times  without  intermission,  in  any  given  number  of  Trials. 

It  was  introduced  in  the  second  edition,  page  243,  in  the  fol- 
lowing terms : 

When  I  was  just  concluding  this  Work,  the  following  Problem  was 
mentioned  to  me  as  very  difficult,  for  which  reason  I  have  considered  it 
with  a  particular  attention. 

De  Moivre  does  not  demonstrate  his  results  for  this  problem  ; 
we  will  solve  the  problem  in  the  modern  way. 

Let  a  denote  the  chance  for  the  event  in  a  single  trial,  h  the 
chance  against  it ;  let  n  be  the  number  of  trials,  p  the  nvimber  of 
times  without  intermission  for  which  the  event  is  required  to  hap- 
pen.    We  shall  speak  of  this  as  a  run  of  p. 

Let  Un  denote  the  probability  of  having  the  required  run  of  ^? 
in  n  trials  ;  then 

«^,i+i  =  y-n  +  (1  -  '^fn-j^  'bdF  : 

for  in  n  +  1  trials  we  have  all  the  favourable  cases  which  we  have 
in  n  trials,  and  some  more,  namely  those  in  which  after  having 
failed  in  n—p  trials,  we  fail  in  the  (n— ^?  +  l)"'  trial,  and  then 
have  a  run  of  p. 


DE   MOIVRE.  185 

Let  Un=l  —Vn,  and  substitute  in  the  equation  ;  thus 
The  Generating  Function  of  v^  will  therefore  be 

where  0  (f)  is  an  arbitrary  function  of  t  which  involves  no  powers 
of  t  higher  than  f. 

The  Generating  Function  of  w„  is  therefore 

1  </>©  . 


1-^   i-t  +  hd'r'' 

we  may  denote  this  by 

t(0 


{1-t)  {\-t  +  ha''r')' 


where  -y^r  (t)  is  an  arbitrary  function  of  t  which  involves  no  powers 
of  t  higher  than  f^^.  Now  it  is  obvious  that  w„  =  0  if  n  be  less 
than  J),  also  u^  =  a^,  and  Up^_^  =  a^  +  ha^. 

Hence  we  find  that 
so  that  the  Generating  Function  of  u„  is 


(1  -  t)  {1  -  t -{- haH'"-')  ' 

The  coefficient  of  f  in  the  expansion  of  this  function  will 
therefore  be  obtained  by  expanding 

a^  (1  -  at) 

i-t  +  loFr^ ' 

and  taking  the  coefficients  of  all  the  powers  of  t  up  to  that  of 
f~^  inclusive. 

It  may  be  shewn  that  De  Moivre's  result  agi'ees  with  this  after 
allowing  for  a  slight  mistake.  He  says  we  must  divide  unity  by 
\—x  —  ax^  —  a^x^  —  ...  —  a^~'^x^,  take  n—jp  +  1  terms  of  the  series, 

multiply  by ^^  ,  and  finally  put  x  = j .  The  mistake  here 


we  ou^lit  to  read  7- .     De  Moivre  is  correct  in  an  example  which 


18G  I)E   MOIVRE. 

is  that  in  the    series  1  -  a?- aa?^-aV  -  ... -a^~V  instead  of  a 

a 
I 

he  gives  on  his  page  255.    Let  j  =Cy  then  according  to  De  Moivre's 

rule  corrected  we  have  to  expand 

1  a^  ,       .  1  —  ex  c? 


a 


\  —  X 


\  —  cx 

This  will  be  seen  to  agree  with  our  result  remembering  that  we 
took  a^h  =  \. 

De  Moivre  himself  on  his  page  256  practically  gives  this  form 
to  his  result  by  putting 

\  —  c^  d^ 

1  —  X  — i for  1  —x^cx"^  —  c^ x^  — . . .  —  (f  ^x^. 

I  —  ex 

De  Moivre  gives  without  demonstration  on  his  page  259  an 
approximate  rule  for  determining  the  number  of  trials  which  must 
be  made  in  order  to  render  the  chance  of  a  run  of  _p  equal  to 
one  half. 

De  Moivre's  Problem  LXXiv.  has  been  extended  by  Condorcet, 
Essai...de  V Analyse...  pages  73 — 86,  and  by  Laplace,  Theorie...des 
Frob.  pages  247 — 253. 

326.  De  Moivre's  pages  261 — 328  are  devoted  to  Annuities  on 
Lives;  an  Appendix  finishes  the  book,  occupying  pages  329 — 348  : 
this  also  relates  principally  to  annuities,  but  it  contains  a  few  notes 
on  the  subject  of  Probability.  As  we  have  already  stated  in 
Art.  53,  we  do  not  profess  to  give  an  account  of  the  investigations 
relating  to  mortality  and  life  insurance. 

We  may  remark  that  there  is  an  Italian  translation  of  De 
Moivre's  treatise  on  Annuities,  with  notes  and  additions ;  the  title 
is  La  Dottrina  degli  Azzardi...de  Ahramo  Moivre:  Trasportata 
dalV  Idionia  Inglese,...dal  Padre  Don  Roberto  Gaeta...sotto  Vassis- 
tenza  del  Padre  Don  Gregorio  Fontana...In  Milano  1776.  This 
translation  does  not  discuss  the  general  Theory  of  Probability,  but 
only  annuities  on  lives  and  similar  subjects. 


DE   MOIVKE.  187 

In  the  Advertisement  to  the  second  edition  of  the  Doctrine  of 
Chances,  page  xiii,  De  Moiwe  says, 

There  is  in  the  World  a  Gentleman  of  an  older  Date,  who  in  the  year 
1726  did  assure  the  Public  that  he  could  calculate  the  Values  of  Lives  if 
he  would,  but  that  he  would  not, . . . 

De  Moivre  proceeds  to  make  some  sarcastic  remarks ;  a  manu- 
script note  in  my  copy  says  that  the  person  here  meant  was 
"John  Smart  of  Guildhall,  who  in  that  year  published  Tables 
of  Interest,  Discount,  Annuities,  &c.  4to." 

327.  "We  have  now  to  notice  De  Moivre's  work  entitled  Mis- 
cellanea  Analytica  de  Seriehus  et  Quadratmns...Ijondoii,  1730. 

This  is  a  quarto  volume  containing  250  pages,  a  page  of  Errata, 
a  Supplement  of  22  pages,  and  two  additional  pages  of  Errata; 
besides  the  title  page,  dedication,  preface,  index,  and  list  of  sub- 
scribers to  the  work. 

We  have  already  had  occasion  to  refer  to  the  Miscellanea 
Analytica  as  supplying  matter  bearing  on  our  subject;  we  now 
however  proceed  to  examine  a  section  of  the  work  which  is  entirely 
devoted  to  controversy  between  Montmort  and  De  Moivre.  This 
section  is  entitled  Responsio  ad  quasdam  Criminationes ;  it  occu- 
pies pages  146 — 229,  and  is  divided  into  seven  Chaj)ters. 

328.  In  the  first  Chapter  the  design  of  the  section  is  ex- 
plained. De  Moivre  relates  the  history  of  the  ]3^iblication  of 
Montmort's  first  edition,  of  the  memoir  De  Mensura  Sor^tis,  and 
of  Montmort's  second  edition.  De  Moi\Te  sent  a  copy  of  the  De 
Mensura  Sortis  to  Montmort,  who  gave  his  opinion  of  the  memoir 
in  a  letter  to  Nicolas  Bernoulli,  which  was  published  in  the  second 
edition  of  Montmort's  book;  see  Art.  221.  De  Moivre  states  briefly 
the  animadversions  of  Montmort,  distributing  them  under  nine 
heads. 

The  publication  of  Montmort's  second  edition  however  does 
not  seem  to  have  produced  any  quarrel  between  him  and  De 
Moivre;  the  latter  returned  his  thanks  for  the  present  of  a  copy 
of  the  work,  and  after  this  a  frequent  interchange  of  letters 
took  place  between  the  two  mathematicians.  In  1715  Montmort 
visited  England,  and  was  introduced  to  Newton  and  other  dis- 


188  DE  MOIVRE. 

tingiilshed  men ;  he  was  also  admitted  as  a  member  of  the  Koyal 
Society.  De  Moivre  sent  to  Montmort  a  copy  of  the  Doctrine  of 
Chances  when  it  was  pubKshed,  and  about  two  years  afterwards 
Montmort  died. 

De  Moivre  quotes  the  words  of  Fontenelle  which  we  have 
already  given  in  Art.  136,  and  intimates  that  these  words 
induced  him  to  undertake  a  comparison  between  his  own  labours 
and  those  of  Montmort,  in  order  to  vindicate  his  own  claims.  As 
the  Doctrine  of  Chances  was  written  in  English  it  was  not  readily 
accessible  to  all  who  would  take  an  interest  in  the  dispute;  and 
this  led  De  Moivre  to  devote  a  section  to  the  subject  in  his  Mis- 
cellanea Analytica. 

329.  The  second  Chapter  of  the  Responsio...  is  entitled  De 
Methodo  Diferentiarum,  in  qua  exhihetur  Solutio  Stirlingiana  de 
media  Coefficiente  Binomii.  The  general  object  is  to  shew  that 
in  the  summation  of  series  De  Moivre  had  no  need  for  any  of 
Montmort's  investigations.  De  Moivre  begins  by  referring  to  a 
certain  theorem  which  we  have  noticed  in  Art.  152;  he  gives  some 
examples  of  the  use  of  this  theorem.  He  also  adverts  to  other 
methods  of  summation. 

Montmort  had  arrived  at  a  very  general  result  in  the  summa- 
tion of  series.  Suppose  u\'^  to  denote  the  n^^  term  of  a  series, 
where  u^  is  such  that  A'^w^  is  zero,  ni  being  any  positive  integer ; 
then  Montmort  had  succeeded  in  summing  any  assigned  number 
of  terms  of  the  series.  De  Moivre  shews  that  the  result  can  be 
easily  obtained  by  the  method  of  Differences,  that  is  by  the  method 
which  we  have  explained  in  Art.  151. 

The  investigations  by  Montmort  on  the  summation  of  series  to 
which  De  Moivre  refers  were  published  in  Vol.  xxx.  of  the  Philo- 
sophical Transactions,  171 7. 

This  Chapter  of  the  Responsio,..  gives  some  interesting  details 
respecting  Stirling's  Theorem  including  a  letter  from  Stirling 
himself. 

330.  The  third  Chapter  of  the  Responsio...  is  entitled  De  Me- 
thodo Comhinatio7ium ;  the  fourth  De  Permutationibus ;  the  fifth 
Combinationes  et  Permutationes  idterius  consideratce :  these  Chap- 


DE  MOIVRE.  189 

ters  consist  substantially  of  translations  of  portions  of  the  DoctHne 
of  Chances,  and  so  do  not  call  for  any  remark.  The  sixth  Chapter 
is  entitled  De  Kumero  PiDictorum  in  Tesseris;  it  relates  entirely 
to  the  formula  of  which  we  have  given  the  history  in  Art.  149. 

331.  The  seventh  Chapter  of  the  Responsio...  is  entitled  Solu- 
tiones  variorum  Prohlematum  ad  Sortem  spectantium.  This  Chapter 
gives  the  solutions  of  nine  problems  in  Chances.  The  first  eight 
of  these  are  in  the  Doctrine  of  Chances ;  nothing  of  importance  is 
added  in  the  Miscellanea  Analytica,  except  in  two  cases.  The  first 
of  these  additions  is  of  some  historical  interest.  Suppose  we  take 
an  example  of  the  Binomial  Theorem,  as  {p  +  qY',  one  term  w^ill 
be  28p^q^:  then  De  Moivre  says,  page  218, 

...at  fortasse  nesciveram  hujus  termini  coefficientem,  nimiruni  28, 
designaturam  numerum  permutationuni  quas  literse  ^9,  p,  p,  p,  p,  p,  q,  q, 
productum  /)^  q'  constituentes  subire  possint ;  immb  vero,  hoc  jam  din 
mihi  erat  exploratum,  etenim  ego  fortasse  primus  omnium  detexi  co- 
efficientes  annexas  productis  Binomii,  vel  Multinomii  cujuscunque,  id 
denotare  quotenis  variationibus  literse  producti  positiones  suas  inter  se 
permuteut:    sed  utrum  illud   facile  fuerit  ad    inveniendum,   j)ostquani 

lex  coefficientium  ex  productis  continuis   :r-   x  — ^r—  x  —= —  x (tc. 

1  z  o  4 

jam  perspecta  esset,  aut  quisquam  ante  me  hoc  ipsum  detexerit,  ad  rem 

prassentem  non  magni  interest,  cum  id  monere  suffecerit  banc  proprie- 

tatem  Coefficientium  a  me  assertam  fuisse  et  demonstratam  in  Actis  FJd- 

losophicis  Anno  1697  impressis. 

The  second  addition  relates  to  Problem  XLix.  of  the  Doctrine 
of  Chances;  some  easy  details  relating  to  a  maximum  value  are 
not  given  there  which  may  be  found  in  the  Miscellanea  Analytica, 
pages  223,  224. 

332.  The  ninth  problem  in  the  seventh  Chapter  of  the  Re- 
sponsio ...  is  to  find  the  ratio  of  the  sum  of  the  largest  p  terms 
in  the  expansion  of  (1  +  1)"  to  the  sum  of  all  the  terms ;  p  being 
an  odd  number  and  7i  an  even  number.  De  Moivre  expresses 
this  ratio  in  terms  of  the  chances  of  certain  events,  for  which 
chances  he  had  already  obtained  formulae.  This  mode  of  ex- 
pressing the  ratio  is  not  given  in  the  Doctrine  of  Chances,  being 
rendered  unnecessary  by  the  application  of  Stirling's  Theorem  ; 


190  DE  moivrp:. 

but  it  involves  an  interesting  fact  in  approximation,  and  we  will 
therefore  explain  it. 

Suppose  two  players  A  and  B  of  equal  skill ;  let  A  have  an 
infinite  number  of  counters,  and  B  have  the  number  j^-  Let 
(j)  [n,p)  denote  the  chance  that  B  will  be  ruined  in  n  games.  Then 
the  required  ratio  is  1  —  (/)  (ii,  p)  ;  this  follows  from  the  first  form 
of  solution  of  Problem  LXV;  see  Art.  307.  Again,  suppose  that 
each  of  the  players  starts  with  p  counters  ;  and  let  -v/r  [n,  p)  then 
denote  the  chance  that  B  will  be  ruined  in  7i  games ;  similarly  if 
each  starts  with  Zp  counters  let  -v/r  {71,  Sp)  denote  the  chance  that 
B  will  be  ruined  in  n  games  ;  and  so  on.  Then  De  Moivre  says 
that  approximately 

^  (??,  p)  =  'f  (n,  p)+'^  (n,  Sp), 

and  still  more  approximately 

The  closeness  of  the  approximation  will  depend  on  n  being 
large,  and  p  being  only  a  moderate  fraction  of  n. 

These  results  follow  from  the  formulse  given  on  pages  199 
and  210  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances...  The  second  term  of 
T^r  {n,  p)  is  negative,  and  is  numerically  equal  to  the  first  term 
of  A|r  {n,  Sj)),  and  so  is  cancelled ;  similarly  the  third  term  of 
'ylr[n,p)  is  cancelled  by  the  first  of  — 'sfr  [n,  5p),  and  the  fourth 
term  of  ^fr  (n,  p)  by  the  first  of  -v/r  (/z,  7p).  The  terms  which  do 
not  mutually  cancel,  and  which  we  therefore  neglect,  involve 
fewer  factors  than  that  which  we  retain,  and  are  thus  com- 
paratively small. 

333.  We  now  proceed  to  notice  the  Supplement  to  the  Mis- 
cellanea Analytica.  The  investigations  of  problems  in  Chances 
had  led  mathematicians  to  consider  the  approximate  calculation 
of  the  coefficients  in  the  Binomial  Theorem ;  and  as  we  shall  now 
see,  the  consequence  was  the  discovery  of  one  of  the  most  striking 
results  in  mathematics.     The  Supplement  commences  thus  : 

Aliquot  post  diebus  qiiam  Liber  qui  inscribitur,  Miscellanea  Analy- 
tica, in  lucem  prodiisset,  Doctissimus  Stlrlingius  me  liteiis  admonuit 
Tabulam  ibi  a  me  exhibitam  de  summis  Logarithmorum,  non  satis  aii- 
toritatis  habere  ad  ea  firmanda  quse  in  speculatione  nitercntur,  utpote 


DE   MO IV RE.  191 

cui  Tabulae  subesset  error  perpetuus  in  quinta  quaque  figura  decimali 
sum  mar  um :  quae  cum  pro  bumauitate  sua  monuisset,  bis  subjunxit 
seriem  celerrime  convergentem,  cujus  ope  summse  logaritbmorum  tot 
numerorum  naturalium  quot  quis  sumere  voluerit  obtineri  possent ; 
res  autem.  sic  exposita  fuerat. 

Then  follows  a  Theorem  which  is  not  quite  coincident  in 
form  with  what  we  now  usually  call  Stirling's  Theorem,  but  is 
practically  equivalent  to  it.  De  Moivre  gives  his  own  investiga- 
tion of  the  subject,  and  arrives  at  the  following  result : 

log  2  +  log  3  +  log  4  +  ...  +  log  (m  —  1) 

=  (m-2)logm-m  +  ^^-3g^3+j260;^.-l^ 
,       1111 


12  '  360      1260  '  1680 

With  respect  to  the  series  in  the  last  line,  De  Moivre  says 
on  page  9,  of  the  Supplement  to  the  Miscellanea  A  nalytica  . . .  quae 
satis  commode  convergit  in  principle,  post  terminos  quinque  pri- 
mes convergentiam  amittit,  quam  tamen  postea  recuperat...  The 
last  four  words  involve  an  error,  for  the  series  is  divergent, 
as  we  know  from  the  nature  of  Bernoulli's  Numbers.  But  De 
Moivre   by  using  a  result  which  Stirling  had  already  obtained, 

111 

arrived  at  the. conclusion  that  the  series  1  —  :r^  +  -rr^  —  =-^— r  +  ... 

12      360      1260 

is  equal  to   -  log  27r ;   and  thus   the   theorem  is  deduced  which 

we  now   call    Stirling's    Theorem.      See   Miscellanea  Analytica, 
page  170,  Supplement,  page  10. 

334.  De  Moivre  proceeds  in  the  Siqyplement  to  the  Miscellanea 
Analytica  to  obtain  an  approximate  value  of  the  middle  coefficient 
of  a  Binomial  expansion,  that  is  of  the  expression 

(W2+1)  (m+2)...  2m 
m  [m  —  1)  ...  1 

He  expends  nearly  two  pages  in  arriving  at  the  result,  which 


192  BE  MOIVRE. 

he  might  have  obtained  immediately  by  putting  the  proposed  ex- 

I  2)n 
pression  in  the  equivalent  form — - . 

De  Moivre  then  gives  the  general  theorem  for  the  approximate 
summation  of  the  series 

1  1,1,1, 

We  have  already  noticed  his  use  of  a  particular  case  of  this 
summation  in  Art.  276. 

De  Moivre  does  not  demonstrate  the  theorem ;  it  is  of  course 

included  in  the  wellknown  result  to  which  Euler's  name  is  usually 

attached, 

^     _  r      ,       1  11  du^       1       1  d^u^ 

See  Novi  Coram.... Petrop.  Vol.  xiv.  part  1,  page  137 ;  1770. 
The   theorem   however   is   also   to   be   found   in    Maclaurin's 
Treatise  of  Fluxions,  1742,  page  673. 

335.  We  return  to  the  Doctrine  of  Chances,  to  notice  what  is 
given  in  its  pages  243 — 254  ;  see  Art.  324. 

In  these  pages  De  Moivre  begins  by  adverting  to  the  theorem 

obtained   by  Stirling  and  himself      He  deduces   from  this   the 

following  result :  suppose  7i  to  be  a  very  large  number,  then  the 

/I      1\" 
logarithm  of  the  ratio  which  a  term  of  I  ^  +  ^ )  ,   distant  from 

the  middle  term  by  the    interval  I,  bears   to  the   middle   term, 

2P 
is  approximately . 

This  enables  him  to  obtain  an  approximate  value  of  the  sum  of 
the  I  terms  which  immediately  precede  or  follow  the  middle  term. 
Hence  he  can  estimate  the  numerical  values  of  certain  chances. 
For  example,  let  n  =  3600  :  then,  supposing  that  it  is  an  even 
chance  for  the  happening  or  failing  of  an  event  in  a  single  trial, 
De  Moivre  finds  that  the  chance  is  '682688  that  in  3600  trials, 
the  number  of  times  in  which  the  event  happens,  will  lie  between 
1800 +  30  and  1800-30. 


DE  MOIVEE.  193 

Thus  by  the  aid  of  Stirling's  Theorem  the  value  of  Bernoulli's 
Theorem  is  largely  increased. 

De  Moivre  adverts  to  the  controversy  between  Nicolas  Ber- 
noulli and  Dr  Arbuthnot,  respecting  the  inferences  to  be  drawn 
from  the  observed  fact  of  the  nearly  constant  ratio  of  the  number 
of  births  of  boys  to  the  number  of  births  of  girls ;  see  Art.  223. 
De  Moivre  shews  that  Nicolas  Bernoulli's  remarks  were  not  re- 
levant to  the  argument  really  advanced  by  Dr  Arbuthnot. 

886.  Thus  we  have  seen  that  the  principal  contributions  to 
our  subject  from  De  Moivre  are  his  investigations  respecting  the 
Duration  of  Play,  his  Theory  of  Recurring  Series,  and  his  extension 
of  the  value  of  Bernoulli's  Theorem  by  the  aid  of  Stirling's  Theorem. 
Our  obligations  to  De  Moivre  would  have  been  still  gi-eater  if  he 
had  not  concealed  the  demonstrations  of  the  important  results 
which  we  have  noticed  in  Art.  306 ;  but  it  will  not  be  doubted 
that  the  Theory  of  Probability  owes  more  to  him  than  to  any 
other  mathematician,  with  the  sole  exception  of  Laplace. 


13 


CHAPTER    X. 

MISCELLANEOUS  INVESTIGATIONS 
Between  the  years  1700  and  1750. 


837.  The  present  Chapter  will  contain  notices  of  various  con- 
tributions to  our  subject  which  were  made  between  the  years  1700 
and  1750. 

338.  The  first  work  which  claims  our  attention  is  the  essay  by 
Nicolas  Bernoulli,  to  which  we  have  already  alluded  in  Art.  72  ;  it 
is  entitled  Specimina  Artis  conjectandi,  ad  quwstiones  Juris  ap- 
plicatce.  This  is  stated  to  have  been  published  at  Basle  in  1709; 
see  Gouraud,  page  STG. 

It  is  reprinted  in  the  fourth  volume  of  the  Act.  Eruditorum.., 
Supplementa,  1711,  where  it  occupies  pages  159 — 170.  Allusion 
is  made  to  the  essay  in  the  volume  which  we  have  cited  in  Art.  59, 
pages  842,  844,  846. 

839.  In  this  essay  Nicolas  Bernoulli  professes  to  apply  mathe- 
matical calculations  to  various  questions,  principally  relating  to  the 
probability  of  human  life.  He  takes  for  a  foundation  some  facts 
which  his  uncle  James  had  deduced  from  the  comparison  of  bills 
of  mortality,  namely  that  out  of  100  infants  born  at  the  same  time 
64  are  alive  at  the  end  of  the  sixth  year,  40  at  the  end  of  the 
sixteenth  year,  and  so  on,  Nicolas  Bernoulli  considers  the  following 
questions  :  the  time  at  the  end  of  which  an  absent  man  of  whom 
no  tidings  had  been  received  might  be  considered  as  dead  ;  the 


NICOLAS   BERNOULLI.  195 

value  of  an  annuity  on  a  life  ;  the  sum  to  be  paid  to  assure  to  a 
child  just  born  an  assigned  sum  on  his  attaining  a  certain  age ; 
marine  assurances  ;  and  a  lottery  problem.  He  also  touches  on  the 
probability  of  testimony ;  and  on  the  probability  of  the  innocence 
of  an  accused  person. 

The  essay  does  not  give  occasion  for  the  display  of  that  mathe- 
matical power  which  its  author  possessed,  and  which  we  have  seen 
was  called  forth  in  his  correspondence  with  Montmort ;  but  it  indi- 
cates boldness,  originality,  and  strong  faith  in  the  value  and  extent 
of  the  applications  which  might  be  made  of  the  Theory  of  Pro- 
bability. 

We  will  take  two  examples  from  the  Essay. 

34:0.  Suppose  there  are  h  men  who  will  all  die  within  a  years, 
and  are  equally  likely  to  die  at  any  instant  ^\dthin  this  time :  re- 
quired the  probable  duration  of  the  life  of  the  last  survivor. 
Nicolas  Bernoulli  really  views  the  problem  as  equivalent  to  the 
following  :  A  line  of  length  a  is  measured  from  a  fixed  origin  ;  on 
this  line  h  points  are  taken  at  random  :  determine  the  mean  dis- 
tance from  the  origin  of  the  most  distant  point. 

Let  the  line  a  be  supposed  divided  into  an  indefinitely  large 
number  n  of  equal  parts ;  let  each  part  be  equal  to  c,  so  that 
nc  =  a. 

Suppose  that  each  of  the  h  points  may  be  at  the  distance 
c,  or  2c,  or  Sc,  ...up  to  nc\  but  no  two  or  more  at  exactly  the 
same  distance. 

Then  the  whole  number  of  cases  will  be  the  number  of  combi- 
nations of  n  things  taken  5  at  a  time,  say  </>  {n,  h). 

Suppose  that  the  most  distant  point  is  at  the  distance  xc  ;  then 
the  number  of  ways  in  which  this  can  happen  is  the  number  of 
ways  in  which  the  remaining  ^  —  1  points  can  be  put  nearer  to  the 
origin  ;  that  is,  the  number  of  combinations  of  a;  —  1  things,  taken 
J  —  1  at  a  time,  say  </>  (a?  —  1,  h  —  1). 

Hence  the  required  mean  distance  is 

^  xc  (j)  {x  —  \,  h  —  V) 

where  the  summation  extends  from  x  =  h  to  x  =  n. 

13—2 


196  BAPvBEYRAC.      ARBUTHNOT. 

TlCu 

It  is  easily  seen  that  the  limit,  when  n  is  infinite,  is  j— ^  ,  that 


IS 


ah 

The  above  is  substantially  the  method  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli. 


341.  Nicolas  BernouUi  has  a  very  curious  mode  of  estimating 
the  probability  of  innocence  of  an  accused  person.  He  assumes 
that  any  single  evidence  against  the  accused  person  is  twice  as 
likely  to  be  false  as  true.  Suppose  we  denote  by  ii^  the  probability 
of  innocence  when  there  are  n  different  evidences  against  him ; 
there  are  two  chances  out  of  three  that  the  n*^'  evidence  is  false, 
and  then  the  accused  prisoner  is  reduced  to  the  state  in  which  there 
are  n  —  1  evidences  against  him ;  and  there  is  one  chance  out  of 
three  that  the  evidence  is  true  and  his  innocence  therefore  impos- 
sible.    Thus 

_  2w„_,jf0  _  2 


.  n 


Hence  ^"~  (sj  * 

This  is  not  the  notation  of  Nicolas ;  but  it  is  his  method  and 
result. 

842.  In  the  correspondence  between  Montmort  and  Nicolas 
Bernoulli  allusion  was  made  to  a  work  by  Barbeyrac,  entitled 
Traits  dii  Jeu;  see  Art.  212.  I  have  not  seen  the  book  myself. 
It  appears  to  be  a  dissertation  to  shew  that  religion  and  morality 
do  not  prohibit  the  use  of  games  in  general,  or  of  games  of  chance 
in  particular.  It  is  stated  that  there  are  two  editions  of  the  work, 
published  respectively  in  1709  and  1744. 

Barbeyrac  is  also  said  to  have  published  a  discourse  Sur  la 
nature  du  Sort 

See  the  English  Cyclopoidia,  and  the  Biographie  Universelle, 
under  the  head  Barbeyrac. 

343.  We  have  next  to  notice  a  memoir  by  Arbuthnot  to  whom 
we  have  already  assigned  an  elementary  work  on  our  subject ; 
see  Art.  79. 

The  memoir  is  entitled  A7i  Argument  for  Divine  Providence, 


ARBUTHNOT,  1Q7 

taken  from  the  constant  Regularity  ohservd  in  the  Births  of  both 
Sexes.  By  Br  John  Arbuthnott,  Physitian  in  Ordinary  to  Her 
Majesty,  and  Felloiu  of  the  College  of  Physitians  and  the  Royal 
Society. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  Vol.  xxvii.  of  the  Philosophical 
Transactions;  it  is  the  volume  for  1710,  1711  and  1712 :  the 
memoir  occupies  pages  186 — 190. 

844.  The  memoir  begins  thus  : 

Among  innumerable  Footsteps  of  Divine  Providence  to  be  found  in 
the  Works  of  Nature,  there  is  a  very  remarkable  one  to  be  observed  in 
the  exact  Ballance  that  is  maintained,  between  the  Numbers  of  Men  and 
Women;  for  by  this  means  it  is  provided,  that  the  Species  may  never  fail, 
nor  perish,  since  every  Male  may  have  its  Female,  and  of  a  proportion- 
able Age.  This  Equality  of  Males  and  Females  is  not  the  Effect  of 
Chance  but  Divine  Providence,  working  for  a  good  End,  which  J  thus 
demonstrate : 

845.  The  registers  of  births  in  London  for  82  years  are  given ; 
these  shew  that  in  every  year  more  males  were  born  than  females- 
There  is  very  little  relating  to  the  theory  of  probability  in  the 
memoir.  The  principal  point  is  the  following.  Assume  that 
it  is  an  even  chance  whether  a  male  or  female  be  born  ;  then 
the  chance  that  in  a  given  year  there  will  be  more  males  than 

females  is  ^ ;  and  the  chance  that  this  will  happen  for  82  years  in 

succession  is  ^ .  This  chance  is  so  small  that  we  may  conclude 
that  it  is  not  an  even  chance  whether  a  male  or  female  be  born. 

846.  The  memoir  attracted  the  attention  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli, 
who  in  his  correspondence  with  Montmort  expressed  his  dissent 
from  Ai'buthnot's  argument ;  see  Art.  223.  There  is  also  a  letter 
from  Nicolas  Bernoulli  to  Leibnitz  on  the  subject ;  see  page  989  of 
the  work  cited  in  Art.  59.  De  Moivre  replied  to  Nicolas  Bernoulli, 
as  we  have  already  intimated  in  Art.  835. 

847.  The  subject  is  also  discussed  in  the  Oemres  Philo- 
sophiques  et  Mathematiques  of  's  Gravesande,  published  at  Amster- 
dam, 1774,  2  vols.  4to.  The  discussion  occupies  pages  221—248 
of  the  second  volume. 


198  'SGKAVESANDE. 

It  appears  from  page  237;  that  when  Nicolas  Bernoulli  travelled 
in  Holland  he  met  'sGravesande. 

In  this  discussion  we  have  first  a  memoir  by  'sGravesande. 
This  memoir  contains  a  brief  statement  of  some  of  the  elements 
of  the  theory  of  probability.  The  following  result  is  then  obtained. 
Assume  that  the  chance  is  even  for  a  male  or  female  birth,  and 
find  the  chance  that  out  of  11429  births  the  males  shall  lie 
between  5745  and  6128.     By  a  laborious  arithmetical  calculation 

1 

this  is  found  to  be  about  -r .     Then  the  chance  that  this  should 

4 

happen  for  82  years  in  succession  will  be  j^ . 

4 

But  in  fact  the  event  for  which  the  chance  is  so  small  had 
happened  in  London.  Hence  it  is  inferred  that  it  is  not  an  even 
chance  that  a  male  or  female  should  be  born. 

It  appears  that  'sGravesande  wrote  to  Nicolas  Bernoulli  on 
the  subject;  the  reply  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli  is  given.  This  reply 
contains  a  jDroof  of  the  famous  theorem  of  James  Bernoulli  ; 
the  proof  is  substantially  the  same  as  that  given  by  Nicolas  Ber- 
noulli to  Montmort,  and  published  by  the  latter  in  pages  389 — 393 
of  his  book. 

Then  'sGravesande  wrote  a  letter  giving  a  very  clear  account 
of  his  views,  and,  as  his  editor  remarks,  the  letter  seems  to  have 
impressed  Nicolas  Bernoulli,  judging  from  the  reply  which  the 
latter  made. 

Nicolas  Bernoulli  thus  sums  up  the  controversy : 

Mr.  Arhutlmot  fait  consister  son  argument  en  deux  cliosesj  1°.  en 
ce  que,  supposee  une  egalite  de  naissance  entre  les  filles  et  les  gargons, 
il  y  a  peu  de  probahilite  que  le  n ombre  des  garyons  et  des  filles  se  trouve 
dans  des  limites  fort  proches  de  I'egalite:  S''.  qu'il  y  a  peu  de  proba- 
hilite que  le  nombre  des  gargous  surpassera  un  grand  nombre  de  fois  de 
suite  le  nombre  des  filles.  C'est  la  premiere  partie  que  je  refute,  et  non 
pas  la  seconde. 

But  this  does  not  fairly  represent  Arbuthnot's  argument. 
Nicolas  Bernoulli  seems  to  have  imagined,  without  any  adequate 
reason,  that  the  theorem  known  by  his  uncle's  name  was  in  some 
way  contradicted  by  Arbuthnot. 

348.     Two   memoirs   on   our   subject   are    published   in   Vol. 


BROWNE.  199 

XXIX.  of  the  Philosopliical  Transactions,  which  is  the  volume  for 
Vjl^,  1715,  1716  the  memoirs  occupy  pages  133 — 158.  They  are 
entitled  Solutio  Generalis  Prohlematis  XV.  2)ro2:)ositi  a  D.  de  Moivre, 
in  tractatii  de  Mensura  Sortie... Solutio  generalis  altera  prcece- 
dentis  Prohlematis,  ope  Comhinationum  et  Serierum  infinitarum.... 

These  memoirs  relate  to  the  problem  which  we  have  called 
Waldegraves ;  see  Art.  211. 

The  first  memoir  is  by  Nicolas  Bernoulli ;  it  gives  substantially 
the  same  solution  as  he  sent  to  Montmort,  and  which  was  printed 
in  pages  381 — 387  of  Montmort's  work. 

The  second  memoir  is  by  De  Moivre ;  it  gives  the  solution 
which  was  reproduced  in  the  Doctrine  of  Chances. 

349.  We  have  next  to  notice  a  work  which  appeared  under 
the  following  title ; 

Christiani  Hugeuii  Libellus  de  Ratiociniis  in  Liido  Alese.  Or,  the 
value  of  all  chances  in  games  of  fortune;  cards,  dice,  wagers,  lotteries,  &c, 
mathematically  demonstrated.  London :  Printed  by  S.  Keimer,  for 
T.  Woodward,  near  the  Inner  Temple-Gate  in  Fleet-street.   1714. 

This  is  a  translation  of  Huygens's  treatise,  by  W.  Browne.  It 
is  in  small  octavo  size ;  it  contains  a  Dedication  to  Dr  Eichard 
Mead,  an  Advertisement  to  the  Header,  and  then  24  pages,  which 
comprise  the  translation.    The  dedication  commences  thus  : 

Honour'd  Sir,  When  I  consider  the  Subject  of  the  following  Papers, 
I  can  no  more  forbear  dedicating  them  to  Your  Name,  than  I  can 
refuse  giving  my  assent  to  any  one  Proposition  in  these  Sciences,  which 
I  have  already  seen  clearly  demonstrated.  The  Reason  is  plain,  for  as 
You  have  contributed  the  greatest  Lustre  and  Glory  to  a  very  consider- 
able part  of  the  Mathematicks,  by  introducing  them  into  their  noblest 
Province,  the  Theory  of  Physick ;  the  Publisher  of  any  Truths  of  that 
Nature,  who  is  desirous  of  seeing  them  come  to  their  utmost  Perfection, 
must  of  course  beg  Your  Patronage  and  Application  of  them.  By  so 
prudent  a  Course  as  this,  he  may  perhaps  see  those  Propositions  which 
ib  was  his  utmost  Ambition  to  make  capable  only  of  directing  Men  in 
the  Management  of  their  Purses,  and  instructing  them  to  what  Chances 
and  Hazards  they  might  safely  commit  their  Money ;  turn'd  some  time 
or  other  to  a  much  more  glorious  End,  and  made  instrumental  likewise 
towards  the  securing  their  Bodies  from  the  Tricks  of  that  too  successful 


200  MAIRAN. 

Sharper,  Death,  and  counterminmg  the  underhand  Dealings  of  secret  and 
overreaching  Distempers. 

In  his  Advertisement  to  the  Reader,  Browne  refers  to  a  trans- 
lation of  Huygens's  treatise  which  had  been  made  by  Arbuthnot ; 
he  also  notices  the  labours  of  Montmort  and  De  Moivre.  He 
says  further. 

My  Design  in  publishing  this  Edition,  was  to  have  made  it  as  useful 
as  possible,  by  an  addition  of  a  very  large  Appendix  to  it,  containing  a 
Solution  of  some  of  the  most  serviceable  and  intricate  Problems  I  cou'd 
think  of,  and  such  as  have  not  as  yet,  that  I  know  of,  met  with  a  par- 
ticular Consideration:  But  an  Information  I  have  within  these  few 
Days  receiv'd,  that  M.  Montmort's  French  Piece  is  just  newly  reprinted 
at  Paris,  with  very  considerable  Additions,  has  made  me  put  a  Stop 
to  the  Appendix,  till  I  can  procure  a  Sight  of  what  has  been  added 
anew,  for  fear  some  part  of  it  may  possibly  have  been  honour'd  with  the 
Notice  and  Consideration  of  that  ingenious  Author. 

I  do  not  know  whether  this  proposed  Appendix  ever  ap- 
peared. 

850.  In  the  Hist  de  V Acad....  Paris  for  1728,  which  was 
published  in  1730,  there  is  a  notice  respecting  some  results  ob- 
tained by  Mairan,  Siir  le  Jeu  de  Fair  ou  Non.  The  notice 
occupies  pages  53 — 57  of  the  volume;  it  is  not  by  Mairan 
himself 

Suppose  a  heap  of  counters  ;  a  person  takes  a  number  of  them 
at  random,  and  asks  another  person  to  guess  whether  the  number 
is  odd  or  even.  Mairan  says  that  the  number  is  more  likely 
to  be  odd  than  even ;  and  he  argues  in  the  following  way.  Sup- 
pose the  number  in  the  heap  to  be  an  odd  number,  for  example  7; 
then  a  person  who  takes  from  the  heap  may  take  1,  or  2,  or  3,  ... 
or  7  counters ;  thus  there  are  7  cases,  namely  4  in  which  he  takes 
an  odd  number,  and  3  in  which  he  takes  an  even  number.  The 
advantage  then  is  in  favour  of  his  having  taken  an  odd  number. 
If  the  number  in  the  heap  be  an  even  number,  then  the  person 
who  takes  from  it  is  as  likely  to  take  an  even  number  as  an 
odd  number.  Thus  on  the  whole  Mairan  concludes  that  the  guess 
should  be  given  for  an  odd  number. 

The  modern  view  of  this  problem  is  different  from  Mairan's. 


NICOLE.  201 

If  the  original  heap  contains  n  counters  we  should  say  that  there 

are  n  ways  of  drawing  one  counter,  -— ^ — ^-^   ways  of  drawing 

two  counters,  and  so  on.  Mairan  notices  this  view  but  con- 
demns it. 

Laplace  treated  this  problem  in  the  Memoires . . .  par  divers 
Savans...TomeYl.,  Paris,  1774,  and  he  arrives  at  the  ordinary  result, 
though  not  by  the  method  of  combinations ;  he  refers  to  Mairan  s 
result,  and  briefly  records  his  dissent.  The  problem  is  solved  by 
the  method  of  combinations  in  the  Theori'e...des  Proh.  page  201. 

In  the  article  Pair  ou  Non  of  the  original  French  Encyclo- 
pedie,  which  was  published  in  1765,  Mairan's  view  is  given ;  this 
article  was  repeated  in  the  Encyclopedie  Methodique,  in  1785, 
without  any  notice  of  Laplace's  dissent. 

351.  On  page  68  of  the  volume  of  the  Hist  de  VAcad.... 
Paris,  which  contains  Mairan's  results,  is  the  following  paragraph : 

M.  L'Abb6  Sauvenr,  fils  de  feu  M.  Sauveur  Academicien,  a  fait  voir 
une  Metliode  qu'il  a  trouvee  pour  determiner  au  Jeu  de  Quadrille  quelle 
est  la  probabilite  de  gagner  sans  prendre  plusieurs  Jeux  differents,  dont 
il  a  calcule  une  Table.  On  a  trouve  que  la  matiere  ej^ineuse  et  delicate 
des  Combinaisons  etoit  tres-bien  entendlie  dans  cet  ouvrage. 

352.  We  have  next  to  notice  a  memoir  by  Nicole,  entitled 
Examen  et  Resolution  de  quelques  questions  sur  les  Jeux. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  volume  for  1730  of  the  Hist, 
de  T Acad.... Paris;  the  date  of  publication  is  1732  :  the  memoir 
occupies  pages  45 — oQ  of  the  part  devoted  to  memoirs. 

The  problem  discussed  is  really  the  Problem  of  Points ;  the 
method  is  very  laborious,  and  the  memoir  seems  quite  superfluous 
since  the  results  had  already  been  given  in  a  simpler  manner  by 
Montmort  and  De  Moivre. 

One  point  may  be  noticed.  Let  a  and  h  be  proportional  to 
the  respective  chances  of  A  and  B  to  win  a  single  game ;  let  them 
play  for  an  even  number  of  games,  say  for  example  8,  and  let 
S  be  the  sum  which  each  stakes.     Then  ^'s  advantage  is 

^  ft8  +  8a^6  +  'iMh''  +  56a^^^  -  b^a'lf  -  28a'h'  -  8ah'  -  b' 

^  {a-^hy  :     • 


202  NICOLE. 

This  supposes  tliat  if  each  wins  four  games,  neither  receives 
nor  loses  any  thing.  Now  it  is  obvious  that  the  numerator  of  the 
expression  is  divisible  by  a  +  h ;  thus  we  may  simplify  the  ex- 
pression to 

This  is  precisely  the  expression  we  should  have  if  the  players 
had  agreed  to  play  seven  games  instead  of  eight.  Nicole  notices 
this  circumstance,  and  is  content  with  indicating  that  it  is  not 
unreasonable ;  we  may  shew  without  difficulty  that  the  result  is 
universally  true.  Suppose  that  when  A  and  B  agree  to  play 
2n  —  l  games,  p^  is  the  chance  that  A  beats  B  by  just  one  game, 
^2  the  chance  that  A  beats  B  by  two  or  more  games ;  and  let 
^j,  q^  be  similar  quantities  with  respect  to  B,  then  ^'s  advantage 
is  S  {p^-\-  p^  —  q^  —  q^.      Now  consider  2n  games  :  ^'s  chance  of 

beating  B  by  two  or  more  games,  is  j?2  +         ?  ;  -S's  chance  of 

beating  A  by  two  or  more  games  is  q^  +    ^^      .     Hence  A's  ad- 
vantage is 


S(p.+ 


^2- 


a  +  b      ^2      a+  bj  ' 
Now  we  know  that  ^  =  ^  =  fj,  say;  therefore 


a 


p^a-qj)      ^{a  ~b)  . 

a  +  b  a  +  b  ^^  i      Lx     i\ 

Hence  the  advantage  of  A  for  2/^  games  is  the  same  as  for 
2/1  —  1  games. 

853.  In  the  same  volume  of  the  Hist,  de  TAcad....Pa7^is,  on 
pages  331 — 344,  there  is  another  memoir  by  Nicole,  entitled 
Methode  jwur  determiner  le  sort  de  taut  de  Joueurs  que  Von 
voudra,  et  Vavantage  que  les  iins  out  sur  les  autres,  lorsqitils 
joilent  h  qui  gagnera  le  plus  de  parties  dans  un  nomhre  de  parties 
determine. 

This  is  the  Problem  of  Points  in  the  case  of  any  number  of 
players,  supposing  that  each  player  wants  the  same  number  of 


BUFFON.  203 

points.  Nicole  begins  in  a  laborious  way;  but  he  sees  tliat  the 
chances  of  the  players  are  represented  by  the  terms  in  the  ex- 
pansion of  a  certain  multinomial,  and  thus  he  is  enabled  to  give 
a  general  rule.  Suppose  for  example  that  there  are  three  players, 
whose  chances  for  a  single  game  are  a,  h,  c.  Let  them  play  a 
set  of  three  games.  Then  the  chance  that  A  has  of  winning 
the  whole  stake  is  a  +  3a^  (^  +  c) ;  and  similar  expressions  give 
the  chances  of  B  and  (7;  there  is  also  the  chance  ^ahc  that  the 
three  players  should  each  win  one  game,  and  thus  no  one  prevail 
over  the  others. 

Similarly,  if  they  play  four  games,  ^'s  chance  of  winning  the 
whole  stake  is  a^ -\-^a  {h  +  c) +  12a^hc\  there  is  also  the  chance 
Wlf  that  A  and  B  should  share  the  stake  between  them  to  the 
exclusion  of  G\  and  so  on. 

But  all  that  Nicole  gives  was  already  well  known ;  see 
Montmort's  page  353,  and  De  Moivi'e's  Miscellanea  Analytica, 
page  210. 

854^.  In  the  year  1733  Bufifon  communicated  to  the  Academy 
of  Sciences  at  Paris  the  solution  of  some  problems  in  chances. 
See  Hist,  de  V Acad.... Pains  for  1733,  pages  43 — 45,  for  a  brief 
account  of  them.  The  solutions  are  given  in  Buffon's  Essai 
dArithm^tique  Morale,  and  we  shall  notice  them  in  speaking 
of  that  work. 

So 5.  We  now  return  to  the  work  entitled  Of  the  Laws  of 
Chance,  the  second  part  of  which  we  left  for  examination  until 
after  an  account  had  been  given  of  De  Moivre's  works ;  see 
Arts.  78,  88. 

According  to  the  title  page  this  second  part  is  to  be  attributed 
to  John  Ham. 

Although  De  Moivre  is  never  named,  I  think  the  greater  part 
of  Ham's  additions  are  taken  from  De  Moivre. 

Ham  considers  the  game  of  Pharaon  in  his  pages  53 — 73.  This 
I  think  is  all  taken  from  De  Moivre,  Ham  gives  the  same  in- 
troductory problem  as  De  Moivi^e ;  namely  the  problem  which 
is  XI.  in  De  Moivre's  first  edition,  and  x.  in  his  third  edition. 

In  pages  74 — 94  we  have  some  examples  relating  to  the  game 
of  Ace  of  Hearts,  or  Fair  Chance,  and  to  Lotteries.     Here  we 


201  HAM. 

have  frequent  use  made  of  De  Moivre's  results  as  to  the  number 
of  trials  in  which  it  is  an  even  chance  that  an  event  will  happen 
once,  or  happen  twice  ;  see  Art.  264. 

856.  There  is  however  an  addition  given  without  demon- 
stration, to  De  Moivre's  results,  which  deserves  notice. 

De  Moivre  made  the  problem  of  finding  the  number  of  trials 
in  which  it  is  an  even  chance  that  an  event  will  occur  twice 
depend  on  the  following  equation  : 

(l  +  ^)' =  2  (1  +  z). 

If  we  suppose  q  infinite  this  reduces  to 

^  =  log  2  +  log  (1  +  ^) ; 

from  which  De  Moivre  obtained  z  =  1-678  approximately.  But  let 
us  not  suppose  q  infinite ;  put  ( 1  +  -j  =6";  so  that  our  equation 

becomes 

6*'^=  2(1+^). 

Assume  z=2  —y,  thus 

Assume  2c  =  7  +  s  where  e*^  =  6. 

1 

Thus,  e*-^  =  1  -  g  y. 


Take  the  logarithms  of  both  sides,  then 

1  1         ,  1         3 


that  is  ''i/  -  Yg  .V'  -  gj  3/'  -  •••  =  ^  ; 

where  r  =  c  —  ^. 

Hence  by  reversion  of  series  we  obtain 


HAM.  205 

This  is  Ham's  formula,   given   as  we  have  said  without  de- 
monstration.    Since  we  assumed 

we  have  7  =  Napierian  log  of  6  =  1-791759  ;  thus 

5  =  2c -7=  2c- 1-791759. 

Ham  says  that  this  series  will  determine  the  value  of  z  in 
all  cases  when  ^  is  greater  than  4-1473.     This  limit  is  doubtless 

obtained  by  making  2c  -  7  =  0,  which   leads  to   (l  +  - j  =  V6  ; 

and   this   can   be   solved   by  trial.     But  Ham  seems  to  be  un- 
necessarily scrupulous  here ;  for  if  2c  be  less  than  7  we  shall  still 

have  -  numerically  less  than  unity,  so  long  as  7  —  2c  is  less  than 
r 

c  -  -^ ,  that  is  so  long  as  c  is  greater  than  k  +  q  . 

357.  The  work  finishes  with  some  statements  of  the  nu- 
merical value  of  certain  chances  at  Hazard  and  Backgammon. 

358.  We  have  next  to  notice  a  work  entitled  Calcul  du  Jeu 
appellS  par  les  Frangois  le  trente-et-quarante,  et  que  Von  nomme 
d  Florence  le  trente-et-un.,,.  Par  Mr  D.  M.  Florence,  1739. 

This  is  a  volume  in  quarto.  The  title,  notice  to  the  reader, 
and  preface  occupy  eight  pages,  and  then  the  text  follows  on 
pages  1 — 90. 

The  game  considered  is  the  following :  Take  a  common  pack 
of  cards,  and  reject  the  eights,  the  nines,  and  the  tens,  so  that 
forty  cards  remain.  Each  of  the  picture  cards  counts  for  ten,  and 
each  of  the  other  cards  counts  for  its  usual  number. 

The  cards  are  turned  up  singly  until  the  number  formed  by 
the  sum  of  the  values  of  the  cards  falls  between  31  and  40,  both 
inclusive.  The  problem  is  to  determine  the  chances  in  favour  of 
each  of  the  numbers  between  31  and  40  inclusive. 

The  problem  is  solved  by  examining  all  the  cases  which  can 
occur,  and  counting  up  the  number  of  ways.  The  operation  is 
most  laborious,  and  the  work  is  perhaps^  the  most  conspicuous 


206  SIMPSON. 

# 

example  of  misdirected  industry  which  the  literature  of  Games 
of  Chance  can  furnish. 

The  author  seems  to  refer  on  page  80  to  another  work  which 
I  have  not  seen.  He  says,  ...j'en  ai  deja  fait  la  demonstration 
dans  mon  Calcul  de  la  Loterie  de  E-ome,... 

It  will  be  observed  from  our  description  of  the  game  that 
it  does  not  coincide  with  that  which  has  been  called  in  more 
recent  times  by  the  same  name.  See  Poisson's  memoir  in  Ger- 
gonne's  Annales  de  Mathe7natiques,  Vol.  16. 

859.  A  treatise  on  the  subject  of  Chances  was  published  by 
the  eminent  Thomas  Simpson,  Professor  of  Mathematics  at  the 
Royal  Military  Academy,  Woolwich.  Simpson  was  born  in  1710, 
and  died  in  1761 ;  an  account  of  his  life  and  writings  is  prefixed 
to  an  edition  of  his  Select  Exercises  for  Young  Proficients  in  the 
Mathematicks,  by  Charles  Hutton. 

Simpson's  work  is  entitled  The  Kature  and  Laws  of  Chance. . . 
The  whole  after  a  new,  general,  and  conspicuous  Manner,  and 
illustrated  luith  a  great  variety  of  Exam^jles  ...  1740. 

Simpson  implies  in  his  preface  that  his  design  was  to  produce 
an  introduction  to  the  subject  less  expensive  and  less  abstruse 
than  De  Moivre's  work  ;  and  in  fact  Simpson's  work  may  be  con- 
sidered as  an  abridgement  of  De  Moivre's.  Simpson's  problems 
are  nearly  all  taken  from  De  Moivre,  and  the  mode  of  treatment 
is  substantially  the  same.  The  very  small  amount  of  new  matter 
which  is  contributed  by  a  writer  of  such  high  power  as  Simpson 
shews  how  closely  De  Moivre  had  examined  the  subject  so  far 
as  it  was  accessible  to  the  mathematical  resources  of  the  period. 

We  will  point  out  what  we  find  new  in  Simpson.  He  divides 
his  work  into  thirty  Problems. 

SCO.     Simpson's  Problem  VI.  is  as  follows  : 

There  is  a  given  Number  of  each  of  several  sorts  of  Things,  (of  the 
s£i,me  Shape  and  Size);  as  {a)  of  the  first  Sort,  (h)  of  the  second,  &c. 
put  promiscuously  together;  out  of  which  a  given  Number  (m)  is  to 
be  taken,  as  it  happens:  To  find  the  Probability  that  there  shall  come 
out  precisely  a  given  Number  of  each  sort,  as  (p)  of  the  first,  {<j)  of 
the  second,  (r)  of  the  third,  &c. 


SIMPSON.  207 

The  result  in  modern  notation  is  a  fraction  of  which  the  nume- 
rator is 

\a  \h  [c 

X  ";         ;    :;  X  X   .  • .  j 


\p  \<^-p    \q\'b-q 


r 


c  —  r 


and  the  denominator  is        : — —•- 


\m\n  —  m 


where  ?z  =  a  +  &  +  c+... 

This  is  apparently  the  problem  which  Simpson  describes  in  his 
title  page  as  '^A  new  and  comprehensive  Problem  of  great  Use  in 
discovering  the  Advantage  or  Loss  in  Lotteries,  Raffles,  &c." 

861.  Simpson's  Problem  x.  relates  to  the  game  of  Bowls  ;  see 
Art.  177.  Simpson  gives  a  Table  containing  results  for  the  case  of 
an  indefinitely  large  number  of  players  on  each  side,  but  he  does 
not  fully  explain  his  Table  ;  a  better  account  of  it  will  be  found  in 
Samuel  Clark's  Laws  of  Chance,  pages  63 — 65. 

S62.  Simpson's  Problem  XV.  is  to  find  in  how  many  trials  one 
may  undertake  to  have  an  equal  chance  for  an  event  to  occur  r 
times,  its  chance  at  a  single  trial  being  known.  Simpson  claims 
to  have  solved  this  problem  "in  a  more  general  manner  than 
hitherto  ;"  but  it  does  not  seem  to  me  that  what  he  has  added  to 
De  Moivre's  result  is  of  any  importance.  We  will  however  give 
Simpson's  addition.     Suppose  we  require   the   event   to  happen 

r  times,    the    chance  for  it  in  a  single  trial  being  j.     Let 

2'  =  -  ;  and  suppose  that  q^  is  large.     Then  De  Moivre  shews  that 

in  order  to  have  an  even  chance  that  the  event  shall  occur  r  times 

we  must  make  about  q  (  ^  ~  tt;  )  trials ;  see  Ai't.  262.     But  if  ^  =  1 

the  required  number  of  trials  is  exactly  2r  — 1.     Simpson  then 

proposes  to  take  as  a  universal  formula  2'(^'~t7v)+^~t^j  this 

is  accurate  when  g[  =  l,  and  extremely  near  the  truth  when  q  is 
large. 


208  SIMPSON. 

363.  Simpson's  Problem  XX.  is  the  same  as  De  Moivre's  Pro- 
blem VII ;  it  is  an  example  of  the  Duration  of  Play  :  see  Art.  107  ; 
Simpson's  method  is  less  artificial  than  that  which  De  Moivre  used, 
and  in  fact  much  resembles  the  modern  method. 

364.  Simpson's  Problem  xxil.  is  that  which  we  have  explained 
in  Art.  148 ;  Simpson's  method  is  very  laborious  compared  with 
De  Moivre's.     Simpson  however  adds  a  useful  Corollary. 

By  introducing  or  cancelling  common  factors  we  may  put  the 
result  of  Art.  148  in  the  following  form  : 

(p'-l){p-2)  ...  (p-n-\-l)  _n  fe-1)  fa- 2). ..(^-72+1) 
\n  —  l  1  1^  —  1 

n{n  —  l)   (r— 1)  (r  —  2)  ...  (r  — n  + 1) 

where  g^—'p-f,  r  —  'p—^f,  ...;  and  the  series  is  to  continue  so 
long  as  no  negative  factors  appear. 

Simpson's  Corollary  then  assigns  the  chance  that  the  sum  of  the 
numbers  exhibited  by  the  dice  shall  not  exceed  p.  We  must  put 
successively  1,  2,  3,  ...  up  to  p  for  p  in  the  preceding  expression, 
and  sum  the  results.  This  gives,  by  an  elementary  proposition 
respecting  the  summation  of  series,  the  following  expression  for  the 
required  chance : 

p{p-l)  ,..{p  —  n-\-l)      n  q{q-V)  ...  (q-n  +  l) 
[n  1  [n 

n(n—l)  r  (r—1)  ...  (r  —  n  +  1) 

where,  as  before,  the  series  is  to  continue  so  long  as  no  negative 
factor  appears. 

365.  Simpson's  Problem  xxiv.  is  the  same  as  De  Moivre's 
LXXiv.,  namely  respecting  the  chance  of  a  run  of  p  successes  in 
n  trials ;  see  Art.  325.  De  Moivre  gave  the  solution  without  a 
demonstration ;  Simpson  gives  an  imperfect  demonstration,  for 
having  proceeded  some  way  he  says  that  the  ''  Law  of  Continuation 
is  manifest." 


SIMPSON.  203 

We  have  shewn  in  effect  that  the  solution  is  obtained  by  taking 
the  coefficient  of  f~^^  in  the  expansion  of 

a^  (1  —  at) 
(1-0  [I  -  t -^^  baH^'-'Y 

that  is  in  the  expansion  of 

a^  (1  -  at) 


{1-ty 


,T  1-at  1         (l-a)t         1  ht 

Now  y, ^=- -+Vt— Tv.=^^ :  + 


(i-ty    i-t'  (1-ty    i-t  '  (1-0'' 

We  can  thus  express  the  result  as  the  sum  of  two  series,  which 
will  be  found  to  agree  with  the  form  given  by  Simpson, 

366.  Simpson's  Problem  XXV.  is  on  the  Duration  of  Play. 
Simpson  says  in  his  Preface  respecting  his  Problems  xxii.  and  xxv, 
that  they  "are  two  of  the  most  intricate  and  remarkable  in  the 
Subject,  and  both  solv'd  by  Methods  entirely  new."  This  seems 
quite  incorrect  so  far  as  relates  to  Problem  xxv.  Simpson  gives 
results  without  any  demonstration ;  his  Case  I.  and  Case  ii.  are 
taken  from  De  Moivre,  his  Case  ill,  is  a  particular  example  of  his 
general  statement  which  follows,  and  this  general  statement  coin- 
cides with  Montmort's  solution ;  see  Montmort,  page  268,  Doctrine 
of  Chances,  pages  193  and  211. 

367.  We  will  give  the  enunciation  of  Simpson's  Problem  XX VI I, 
together  with  a  remark  which  he  makes  relating  to  it  in  his 
Preface. 

In  a  Parallelopipedon,  whose  Sides  are  to  one  another  in  the  Ratio 
of  a,  6,  cj  To  find  at  how  many  Throws  any  one  may  undertake  that 
any  given  Plane,  viz,  ah,  may  arise. 

The  27th  is  a  Problem  that  was  proposed  to  the  Public  some  time 
ago  in  Latin,  as  a  very  difficult  one,  and  has  not  (that  I  know  of) 
been  answered  before. 

We  have  seen  the  origin  of  this  problem  in  Ai't.  87.  Simpson 
supposes  that  a  sphere  is  described  round  the  paralleleiDiped,  and 
that  a  radius  of  the  sphere  passes  round  the  boundary  of  the  given 
plane;   he  considers  that  the  chance  of  the  given  plane  being 

li 


210  SIMPSON. 

uppermost  in  a  single  throw  is  equal  to  the  ratio  which  the  spheri- 
cal surface  bounded  by  the  moving  radius  bears  to  the  whole 
surface  of  the  sphere.  Thus  the  problem  is  reduced  to  finding  the 
area  of  a  certain  portion  of  the  surface  of  a  sphere. 

868.     Simpson  gives  two  examples  of  the  Summation  of  Series 
on  his  pages  70 — 73,  which  he  claims  as  new  in  method. 

(1)     Let  {a  +  xy  be  denoted  hj  A-\-Bx-\-  Cx^  +  Dx""  +  . . . ; 
required  the  sum  of 

A  Bx  Cx' 

1.2...r"^2.3...  (r  +  l)"^S.4...(r  +  2)"^**'* 

'  Integrate  both  sides  of  the  identity,  and  determine  the  con- 
stant so  that  both  sides  may  vanish  when  a?  =  0  ;  thus 

{a  +  xY^'       g"-^^   _    .        Bx^      Cx^     Bx"^ 
71  +  1        n-\-\  2         3         4 

Repeat  the  operation  ;  thus 


(?i  +  l)(n+2)      n  +  1      (n+l)(7^  +  2) 

_A^      B^      C'^      Dx^ 
~'1.2"^2.3"^3T4"^4.5"^"" 

Proceed  thus  for  r  operations,  then  divide  both  sides  by  a?*",  and 
the  required  sum  is  obtained. 

(2)     Required  the  sum  of  1"  +  2«  +  8"  +  . . .  +  ic". 

Simpson's  method  is  the  same  as  had  been  already  used  by 
Nicolas  Bernoulli,  who  ascribed  it  to  his  uncle  John ;  see  Art.  207. 

869.     Simpson's  Problem  xxix.  is  as  follows  : 

A  and  B,  whose  Chances  for  winning  any  assigned  Game  are  in 
the  proportion  of  a  to  6,  agree  to  play  until  7i  stakes  are  won  and 
lost,  on  Condition  that  A,  at  the  Beginning  of  every  Game  shall  set 

the  Sum  p  to  the  Sum  ^x-,  so  that  tliey  may  play  without  Disad- 

ct 

vantage  on  either  Side;  it  is  required  to  find  the  present  Value  of  all 
the  Winnings  that  may  be  betwixt  them  when   the  Play  is  ended. 

The  investigation  presents  no  difficulty. 


SIMPSON.  211 

870.  Simpson's  Problem  xxx.  is  as  follows : 

Two  Gamesters,  A  and  £,  equally  skilful,  enter  into  Play  together, 
and  agree  to  continue  the  same  till  (n)  Games  are  won  and  lost.  'Tis 
required  to  find  the  Probability  that  neither  comes  off  a  Winner  of 
Q'Jn  Stakes,  and  also  the  Probability  that  B  is  never  a  Winner  of 
that  Number  of  Stakes  during  the  whole  Time  of  the  Play;  r  being 
a  given,  and  n  any  very  great,  Number, 

Simpson  says  in  bis  Preface  relating  to  bis  Problems  XXIV.  and 
XXX.  tbat  tbey 

"  are  the  same  with  the  two  new  ones,  added  in  the  End  of  Mr 
Be  Moivre's  last  Edition,  whose  Demonstrations  that  learned  Author 
was  pleased  to  reserve  to  himself,  and  are  here  fully  and  clearly  in- 
vestigated...." 

The  same  two  problems  are  thus  referred  to  in  Simpson's 
title  page : 

Full  and  clear  Investigations  of  two  Problems,  added  at  the  end  of 
Mr.  De  Moivre's  last  Edition ;  one  of  them  allowed  by  that  great  Man 
to  be  the  most  useful  on  the  Subject,  but  their  Demonstrations  there 
omitted. 

Simpson  is  quite  wrong  in  claiming  tbe  solution  of  Pro- 
blem XXX,  and  saying  that  De  Moivre  had  reserved  his  demon- 
stration to  himself.  The  investigation  is  that  for  determining  the 
approximate  value  of  terms  near  the  largest  in  the  expansion  of 
{a  +  hy ;  it  is  given  in  the  Doctrine  of  Chances,  second  edition, 
pages  233 — 243,  third  edition  pages  241 — 2ol  :  the  method  of 
Simpson  is  in  fact  identical  with  De  Moivre's. 

871.  We  may  remark  that  Simpson  published  a  work  in  l7o7 
under  the  title  of  Miscellaneous  Tracts  on  some  curious,  and 
very  interesting  Subjects  in  Mechanics,  Physical- Astronomy,  and 
Speculative  Mathematics ; ... 

In  this  work  on  pages  64 — 75  we  have  a  section  entitled  An 
Attempt  to  shew  the  Advantage  arising  by  Taking  the  Mean  of  a 
Number  of  Observations,  in  Practical  Astronomy. 

This  is  a  very  interesting  section ;  the  problems  solved  by 
Simpson  were  reproduced  by  Lagrange  in  a  memoir  in  the  fifth 
volume  of  the  Miscellanea  Taurinensia,  without  any  allusion  how- 
ever to  Simpson. 

14—2 


212  JOHN   BERNOULLI. 

It  will  be  more  convenient  to  defer  any  account  of  the  section 
in  Simpson  until  we  examine  Lagrange's  memoir,  and  then  we  will 
state  what  Simpson  gave  in  17 o7. 

372.  The  fourth  volume  of  the  collected  edition  of  John  Ber- 
noulli's works,  which  was  published  in  1742  has  a  section  entitled 
De  Alea,  sive  Arte  Conjectandi,  Prohlemata  qucedam;  this  section 
occupies  pages  28 — 33  :  it  contains  seven  problems. 

373.  The  first  and  second  problems  are  simple  and  well- 
known  ;  they  are  solved  completely.  The  third  problem  relates  to 
the  game  of  Bowls  ;  John  Bernoulli  gives,  without  demonstration, 
the  result  which  had  already  been  published ;  see  Montmort, 
page  248,  and  the  Doctrine  of  Chances,  page  117. 

374.  The  fourth  problem  contains  an  error.  John  Bernoulli 
sa3"s  that  if  2n  common  dice  are  thrown,  the  number  of  ways  in 
which  the  sum  of  the  marks  is  7n  is 

(7n-l)  (7^-2)(7n-3)...(5yz  +  l)  . 
1.2.3.4  ...  (2?z-l)  * 

this  amounts  to  asserting  that  the  expression  here  given  is  the  co- 
efficient of  x""  in  the  expansion  of 

.  (ic  +  a?'  -I-  a;'  +  a;'  +  x\+  x^  : 

in  fact  however  the  coefficient  is  a  series  of  which  the  above  ex- 
pression is  only  the  first  term. 

375.  The  fifth  and  sixth  problems  involve  nothing  new  in 
principle ;  John  Bernoulli  gives  merely  the  numerical  results  which 
would  require  long  calculation  to  verify.  The  seventh  problem 
does  not  seem  intelligible. 


CHAPTER  XL 


DANIEL  BERNOULLI. 

376.  Daxiel  Beexoulli  was  the  son  of  the  John  Bernoulli 
to  whom  we  have  often  referred ;  Daniel  was  born  in  1700,  and 
died  in  1782  :  he  is  the  author  of  some  important  memoirs  on 
our  subject,  remarkable  for  their  boldness  and  originality,  which 
we  shall  now  proceed  to  examine. 

377.  Tlie  first  memoir  which  we  have  to  notice  is  entitled 
Specimen  TJieornce  Xovcb  de  Mensura  Sortis.  This  memoir  is 
contained  in  the  Commentarii  Acad.  ...Petrop.  Vol.  v.,  which  is 
the  volume  for  the  years  1730  and  1731 ;  the  date  of  publication 
of  the  volume  is  1738  :  the  memoir  occupies  pages  175 — 192. 

378.  This  memoir  contains  the  theory  of  Moral  expectation 
proposed  by  Daniel  Bernoulli,  which  he  considered  would  give 
results  more  in  accordance  with  our  ordinary  notions  than  the 
theory  of  Mathematical  expectation.  Laplace  has  devoted  to  this 
subject  pages  432 — 415  of  his  Theorie...des  Proh.,  in  which  he 
reproduces  and  developes  the  hypothesis  of  Daniel  Bernoulli. 

379.  Mathematical  expectation  is  estimated  by  the  product 
of  the  chance  of  obtaining  a  sum  of  money  into  that  sum.  But 
we  cannot  in  practice  suppose  that  a  given  sum  of  money  is  of 
equal  importance  to  every  man ;  a  shilling  is  a  matter  of  small 
moment  to  a  person  who  possesses  a  thousand  pounds,  but  it  is 
of  great  moment  to  a  person  who  only  possesses  a  few  shillings. 
Various  hj^otheses  may  be  proposed  for  taking  into  account  the 


214  DANIEL  BERNOULLI. 

relative  value  of  money ;  of  these  Daniel  Bernoulli's  has  attracted 
most  notice. 

Suppose  a  person  to  possess  a  sum  of  money  x,  then  if  it  re- 
ceive an  increment  dx,  Daniel  Bernoulli  estimates  the  relative 
value  of  the  increment  as  proportional  to  dx  directly  and  x  in- 

ndx 

versely ;  that  is,  he  takes  it  equal  to  where  Jc  is  some  con- 

stant.      Put  this  equal  to  Jt/  ;  so  that 

■J  ruCtX 

dy  = ; 

therefore  y  —  T^  log  ^  +  constant 

=  Ti  log  -  say. 

Laplace  calls  x  the  fortune  physique  and  y  the  fortune  morale. 
"We  must  suppose  a  some  positive  quantity,  for  as  Daniel  Bernoulli 
remarks,  no  man  is  absolutely  destitute  unless  he  is  dying  of 
hunger. 

Daniel  Bernoulli  calls  y  the  emolumentum,  a  he  calls  summa 
honorum,  and  x  —  a  he  calls  lucrum. 

880.  Suppose  then  that  a  person,  starting  with  a  for  his  fortune 
physique,  has  the  chance  p^^  of  gaining  a?^,  the  chance  p^  of  gaining 
x^,  the  chance  p^  of  gaining  x^,  and  so  on ;  and  suppose  the  sum 
of  these  chances  to  be  unity.     Let 

Y=  hp^  log  {a  +  x^  +  hp^  log  {a-\-x,^  -\-  hp^  log  (a  +  i^Cg)  + . . .  —  ^  log  a. 

Then  Bernoulli  calls  Y  the  emolumentum  medium,  and  Laplace 
still  calls  Y  the  fortune  morale.  Let  X  denote  the  fortune 
physique  which  corresponds  to  this  fortune  morale ;  then 

Y=h  log  X—h  log  a. 

Thus  X  =  (a  +  cc/^  («  +  xf^  {a  +  x^""'  . . . 

And  X—a  will  be  according  to  Laplace  V accroissement  de  la 
fortune  physique  qui  procurerait  a  Tindividu  le  menie  avantage 
moral  qui  r4sidte  pour  lui,  de  son  expectative.  Daniel  Bernoulli 
calls  X—a  the  liicru7n  legitime  expectandum  seu  so7^s  quwsita. 


DANIEL  BERNOULLI.  215 

381.  Daniel  Bernoulli  in  his  memoir  illustrates  his  hy- 
pothesis by  drawing  a  curve.     He  does  not  confine  himself  to  the 

case   in   which  ^  =  7c  log  -  ,    but    supposes   generally  2/  =  </>  (x). 

Thus  the  ordinary  theory  of  mathematical  expectation  amounts  to 
supposing  that  the  curve  becomes  a  straight  line,  or  (p  (x)  a 
linear  function  of  x. 

382.  After  obtaining  the  value  of  X  which  we  have  given 
in  Art.  380,  the  remainder  of  Daniel  Bernoulli's  memoir  consists 
of  inferences  drawn  from  this  value. 

383.  The  first  inference  is  that  even  a  fair  game  of  chance 
is  disadvantageous.  Suppose  a  man  to  start  with  a  as  his  fortune 
physique,  and  have  the  chance  p^  of  gaining  x^,  and  the  chance 
p^  of  losing  x^.  Then  by  Art.  380,  the  fortune  physique  which  he 
may  expect  is 

{a  +  a?/'  (a  -  x^^^ ; 

we  have  to  shew  that  this  is  less  than  a,  supposing  the  game  to  be 
mathematically  fair,  so  that 

Daniel  Bernoulli  is  content  with  giving  an  arithmetical  ex- 
ample, supposing  i>i  =/>2  =  2  •     I^aplace  establishes  the  proposition 

generally  by  the  aid  of  the  Integral  Calculus.  It  may  be  proved 
more  simply.     We  have 

x^  x^ 

■^^  ~  iCj  +  a?/     ^^"aj^  +  iCg' 

and  we  have  to  shew  that 

[[a-^x^'^'ia-x^"''^^'  is  less  than  a. 

Now  we  may  regard  x^  and  x^  as  integers.  Thus  the  result 
we  require  is  true  by  virtue  of  the  general  theorem  in  inequalities 
that  the  geometrical  mean  is  less  than  tlie  arithmetical  mean.     For 


216  DANIEL   BERNOULLI. 

here  we  may  suppose  that  there  are  x^  quantities,  each  equal  to 
a  +  iCj,  and  x^  quantities  each  equal  to  a  —  iCg.  The  arithmetical 
mean  is 

'^2   (^  +  ^l)   +  ^1   (<^  -  ^2) 

—  J 

^1  +  ^2 

that  is  a.  The  geometrical  mean  is  the  quantity  which  we  had 
to  shew  to  be  less  than  a. 

884.  Daniel  Bernoulli   proposes  to  determine  what   a  man 
should  stake  at  a  wager,  in  order  that  the  wager  may  not  be 

disadvantageous  to  him.  He  takes  the  case  in  which  'p^—]p^  —  -^  . 
Then  we  require  that 

(a  +  icj^  {a  —  x^^  —  a. 

This  leads  to  x^  — —  . 

Thus  x^  is  less  than  x^  and  less  than  a. 

885.  Daniel  Bernoulli  now  makes  an  application  to  in- 
surances. But  this  application  will  be  more  readily  understood  if 
we  give  first  a  proposition  from  Laplace  which  is  not  in  Daniel 
Bernoulli's  memoir.  Suppose  that  a  merchant  has  a  fortune 
physique  equal  to  a,  and  that  he  expects  the  sum  x  to  arrive 
by  a  ship.  Also  let  p  be  the  chance  that  the  ship  will  arrive 
safely,  and  lei  q  =  l  —p. 

Suppose  that  he  insures  his  ship  on  the  ordinary  terms  of 
mathematical  equity ;  then  he  pays  qx  to  the  insurance  company, 
so  that  he  has  on  the  whole  a  +  x  —  qx,  that  is  a  -\-px. 

Suppose  however  that  he  does  not  insure ;  then  his  fortune 
physique  is  (a  +  xfa'^.  We  shall  shew  that  a-\-px  is  greater 
than  {a  +  xYa^. 

Laplace  establishes  this  by  the  aid  of  the  Integral  Calculus, 
with  which  however  we  may  dispense.     We  have  to  shew  that 

(a  +  xYa^  is  less  than  a  +px, 

that  is  that  (1  +  -  )    is  less  than  1  +  -^ . 

\        a/  a 


DANIEL   BERNOULLI.  2l7 


Let  »  = where  m  and  n  are  integers. 

Then  we  know  that  [{l  +  ^)"  l'^  1^^  is  less  than 

m  +n 

by  the  theorem  respecting  the  geometrical  mean  and  the  arith- 

metrical  mean  which  we  quoted  in  Art.  383  ;  and  this  is  what  we 

had  to  establish. 

It  follows  that  the  merchant  can  afford  without  disadvantage 

to  increase  his  payment  to  the  insurance  company  beyond  the 

sum  qx.     If  we  suppose   f  to  represent  the  extreme   additional 

sum,  we  have 

f  =  a  +jyx  —  (a  +  ic)  V. 

886.  We  now  return  to  Daniel  Bernoulli.  We  have  seen 
that  a  merchant  can  afford  to  pay  more  than  the  sum  qx  for 
insuring ;  but  it  may  happen  that  the  insurance  company  demand 
more  than  the  merchant  can  afford  to  pay.  Daniel  Bernoulli 
proposes  this  question :  for  a  given  charge  by  the  insurance  com- 
pany required  to  find  the  merchant's  fortune,  so  that  it  may 
be  indifferent  to  him  whether  he  insures  or  not. 

Retaining  the  notation  of  the  last  Article,  let  e  be  the  charge 
of  the  insurance   company ;    then  we  have  to  find  a  from  the 

equation 

a-\-x  —  e  =  {a  +  xYa^ 

19 

Daniel  Bernoulli  takes  for  an  example  a?= 10000,  e=800,^=  ^  ; 

whence  by  approximation  a—  5043.  Hence  he  infers  that  if  the 
merchant's  fortune  is  less  than  5043  he  ought  to  insure,  if  greater 
than  5043  he  ought  not  to  insure.  This  amounts  to  assuming 
that  the  equation  from  which  a  is  to  be  found  has  only  one 
positive  root.  It  may  be  interesting  to  demonstrate  this.  We 
have  to  compare 

a-\-x  —  e  with  {a  +  ic)^a^ 

where  a  is  the  variable,  and  x  is  greater  than  e. 


218  DANIEL  BERNOULLI. 

Let  p  =  — ; —  SLiid  q=  — ; — ,  where  m  and  n  are  inteofers  : 

then  we  have  to  compare 

{a  +  x-  eY^*"  with  {a  +  xY  a\ 

Wlien  a  =  0  the  right-hand  member  is  the  less  ;  when  a  is 
infinite  the  right-hand  member  is  the  greater,  provided  mx  is 
greater  than  (m  -^  n)  [x  —  e)  :  we  will  assume  that  this  is  the  case. 
Thus  the  equation 

{a-^x-  e)'""-"  =  (a  +  xY  oT 

has  one  positive  root.     We  must  examine  if  it  has  another. 

Let      log  {a  +  x-  ef'^''  =  y,         log  (a  +  xY  dr  =  z\ 

.  dy        m-\-n  dz         m         n 

then  -  -f  =  — , ,        -7-  =  — , h  -  . 

da     a  +  X  —  e  da     x  +  a     a 

d z  d  II 

Thus  when  a  is  zero  -j-  is  greater  than  j- ,  so  that  z  begins 

by  increasing  more  rapidly  tlian  y  does.     If  we  suppose 

dy     dz 
da     da 

* 

,  ,   .  nx  (x  —  e) 

we  obtam  a  =  - — — ^r '■—  . 

(??i  -\-n)  e  —  nx 

Now  begin  with  a  =  0,  and  let  a  gradually  increase  until  we 
have  y  =  z\  then  it  is  obvious  that  we  have  not  yet  reached  the 
value  of  a  just  given.  And  if  by  increasing  a  we  could  arrive 
at  a  second  value  at  which  y  =  z,  we  should  have  passed  beyond 
the  value  of  a  just  given.  Then  after  that  value  z  would  increase 
more  slowly  than  y,  and  the  final  value  of  z  would  be  less  than 
the  final  value  of  y,  which  is  impossible.  Thus  there  is  only  one 
value  of  a  which  makes  y  =  z,  and  this  value  is  less  than 

nx  {x  —  e) 
{m  ■\-  n)  e  —  nx' 

If  mx  is  less  than  (m  -\-n)  {x  —  e)  the  original  equation  has 
no  positive  root;  for  then  we  have  z  always  increasing  more 
rapidly  than  y,  and  yet  the  final  value  of  z  less  than  that  of  y ; 
so  that  it  is  impossible  that  any  value  of  a  can  make  y  =  z. 


DANIEL  BERNOULLI.  219 

387.  Daniel  Bernoulli  also  inquires  what  capital  the  in- 
surance company  must  have  so  that  they  may  safely  undertake 
the  insurance.  Let  y  denote  the  least  value  of  the  capital ;  then 
y  must  be  found  from 

This  is  merely  the  former  equation  with  y  in  place  of  a  +  ic  —  e. 
Thus,  taking  the  same  example  as  before,  we  have^  =  ltt2^3. 

888.     Daniel  Bernoulli  now  lays  down  the  important  principle 

that  it  is  more  advantageous  for  a  person  to  expose  his  fortune 

to  different  independent  risks  than  to  expose  it  all  to  one  risk. 

He  gives   this   example :    suppose   a  merchant  to   start   with  a 

9 
capital  of  4000,  and  that  he    expects   8000  by  a  ship ;   let  — 

be  the  chance  of  the  safe  arrival  of  the  ship.     The  merchant's 
fortune  'physiqiie  is  thus 

(4000  +  8000)T^  (4000)^=10751  approximately. 

But  suppose  him  to  put  half  of  his  merchandize  in  one  ship 

and  half  in  another.    The  chance  that  both  ships  will  arrive  safely 

81 
is  r7^\  the   chance  that  one  of  the  two   will   amve  safely  is 
100  '' 

9        1  18 

2  X  Y^  X  — r ,  that  is  —— ;  the  chance  that  both  will  be  lost  is 

1 

r— X  .     Hence  the  merchant's  fortune  'physique  is 

(4000  +  8000)tV(7  (4000  +  4000)^^  (4000)^^=  11033 
approximately. 

Subtract  the  original  capital  4000,  and  we  find  the  expectation 
in  the  former  case  to  be  6751,  and  in  the  latter  to  be  7033. 

Daniel  Bernoulli  says  that  the  merchant's  expectation  con- 
tinually increases  by  diminishing  the  part  of  the  merchandize 
which  is  intrusted  to  a  single  ship,  but  can  never  exceed  7200. 

9 

This  number  is  —  of  8000 ;  so  that  it  expresses  the  Mathematical 

expectation.     The  result  which  Daniel  Bernoulli  thus  enunciates. 


220  DANIEL   BERNOULLI. 

without  demonstration  is  demonstrated  by  Laplace,  Theorie  . . .  des 
Froh.,  pages  435 — 437 ;  the  proposition  is  certainly  by  no  means 
easy,  and  it  is  to  be  wished  that  Daniel  Bernoulli  had  explained 
how  he  obtained  it. 

389.  Daniel  Bernoulli  now  applies  his  theory  to  the  problem 
which  is  known  as  the  Petershurg  Problem,  probably  from  its  first 
appearing  here  in  the  Coiiimentarii  of  the  Petersburg  Academy. 
The  problem  is  similar  to  two  which  Nicolas  Bernoulli  proposed  to 
Montmort;  see  Art.  231. 

A  throws  a  coin  in  the  air ;  if  head  appears  at  the  first  throw 
he  is  to  receive  a  shilling  from  B,  if  head  does  not  appear  until  the 
second  throw  he  is  to  receive  2  shillings,  if  head  does  not  appear 
until  the  third  throw  he  is  to  receive  4  shillings,  and  so  on :  re- 
quired the  expectation  of  A. 

The  expectation  is 

1  2       4       8,        ...   V 

2  +  22  +  2^  +  2^  +  •  •  •  ^^^  'infinitum, 

that  is  ^  +  ^  +  2  +  9  +  •  • .  ^'^^  infinitum. 

Thus  ^'s  expectation  is  infinite,  so  that  he  ought  to  give  an 
infinite  sum  to  B  to  induce  B  to  play  with  him  in  the  manner 
proposed.  Still  no  prudent  man  in  the  position  of  A  would  be 
willing  to  pay  even  a  small  number  of  shillings  for  the  advantage 
to  be  gained. 

The  paradox  then  is  that  the  mathematical  theory  is  apparently 
directly  opposed  to  the  dictates  of  common  sense. 

390.  We  will  now  give  Daniel  Bernoulli's  application  of  his 
theory  of  Moral  expectation  to  the  Petersburg  Problem. 

Suppose  that  A  starts  with  the  sum  a,  and  is  to  receive  1  if 
head  appears  at  the  first  throw,  2  if  head  does  not  appear  until  the 
second  throw,  and  so  on.     ^'s  fortune  physique  is 

{a  +  1)^  {a  +  2)^  {a  +  4)^  (a  +  8)^^  ...  -  a. 

This  expression  is  finite  if  a  be  finite.  The  value  of  it  when 
a  =  0  is  easily  seen  to  be  2.  Daniel  Bernoulli  says  that  it  is  about 
8  when  a  =  10,  about  4  J  when  a  =  100,  and  about  6  when  a  =  1000. 


DANIEL   BEKNOULLI.  221 

Let  X  represent  the  sum  which  a  person  with  the  capital  a 
might  give  without  disadvantage  for  the  expectation  of  A  \  then  x  is 
to  be  found  from 

(a  +  1  —  a?)^  (a  +  2  —  a?)^  (a  +  4  —  x)^  (a  +  8  —  x)^  . ..  =  a. 

Put  a  —  X  —  a  \  thus 

{a  +  1)^  [a  +  2)^  (a'  +  4)^  {a  +  8)tV  ...  -  a'  =  a;. 

Then  if  a  is  to  have  any  large  value,  from  what  we  have 
already  seen,  x  is  small  compared  with  a,  so  that  we  may  put  a  for 
a  \  and  we  have  approximately 

a;  =  (a +  1)^  (a +  2)^  (a +  4)^  (a +  8)^...  -a. 

Laplace  reproduces  this  part  of  Daniel  Bernoulli's  memoir  with 
developments  in  pages  439 — 442  of  the  Theorie...des  Proh. 

391.  Daniel  Bernoulli's  memoir  contains  a  letter  addressed  to 
Nicolas  Bernoulli  by  Cramer,  in  which  two  methods  are  suggested 
of  explaining  the  paradox  of  the  Petersburg  Problem. 

(1)  Cramer  considers  that  the  value  of  a  sum  of  money  is  not 
to  be  taken  uniformly  proportional  to  the  sum ;  he  proposes  to 
consider  all  sums  greater  than  2^"^  as  practically  equal.  Thus  he 
obtains  for  the  expectation  of  B 

1      2       4  2^^ 

2*^2^ 


"■"  02   "■"  03  "•"•••     •     '^"•5 


924  924  924 

'     926   "^  927  "'     928  "1"    •••• 

The  first  twenty-five  terms  give  12 J;  the  remainder  constitute 

a  geometrical  progression  of  which  the  sum  is  ^ .     Thus  the  total 
is  13. 

(2)  Cramer  suggests  that  the  pleasure  derivable  from  a  sum 
of  money  may  be  taken  to  vary  as  the  square  root  of  the  sum. 
Thus  he  makes  the  moral  expectation  to  be 

2  a/I  +  J  V2  +  g  v/4  +  ^  V8  +■ . . . , 

that  is j^ .      This  moral  expectation  corresponds  to  the  sum 


222  DANIEL   BERNOULLI. 

1 


rg-,  that  is  to  2 "9  approximately;   and  Cramer  considers 

(2  —  V2) 

this  to  be  nearer  the  comm.on  notion  on  the  subject  than  his  former 
value  13. 

892.  It  is  obvious  that  Cramer's  suppositions  are  entirely 
arbitrary,  and  that  such  suppositions  might  be  multiplied  to  any 
extent.  Montucla  alludes  on  his  page  403  to  an  attempt  made  by 
M.  Fontaine  to  explain  the  paradox.  This  attempt  seems  to  con- 
sist in  limiting  the  game  to  20  throws  at  most,  instead  of  allowing 
it  theoretically  to  extend  to  infinity.  But  the  opponents  of  the 
mathematical  theory  would  assert  that  for  the  game  as  thus  under- 
stood the  value  of  the  expectation  assigned  by  the  theory  is  still 
far  larger  than  common  sense  can  admit. 

393.  The  Petersburg  Problem  will  come  under  our  notice 
again  as  we  advance  with  the  subject.  We  may  remark  that 
Laplace  adopts  Daniel  Bernoulli's  view  ;  Theorie . . .  des  Proh. 
page  439.  Poisson  prefers  to  reconcile  mathematical  theory  with 
common  sense  by  the  consideration  that  the  fortune  of  the  person 
whom  we  represent  by  B  is  necessarily  finite  so  that  he  cannot  pay 
more  than  a  certain  sum ;  this  in  result  practically  coincides  with 
the  first  of  Cramer's  two  suppositions ;  see  Poisson,  RechercJies 
sur  la  Proh...  page  73;  Cournot,  Exposition  de  la  Theorie  des 
Chances...  page  108. 

894.  We  pass  to  another  memoir  by  Daniel  Bernoulli.  The 
Academy  of  Sciences  of  Paris  proposed  the  following  question  as  a 
prize  subject  for  1732, 

Quelle  est  la  cause  physique  de  rinclinaison  des  Plans  des  Orbites 
des  Planetes  par  rapport  au  plan  de  I'Equateur  de  la  revolution  du 
Soleil  autour  de  son  axe;  Et  d'oii  vient  que  les  inclinaisons  de  ces 
Orbites  sont  differentes  entre  elles. 

None  of  the  memoirs  sent  in  appeared  to  the  judges  to  be 
worthy  of  the  prize.  The  Academy  then  proposed  the  subject 
again  for  1734,  with  a  double  prize.  The  prize  was  divided  be- 
tween Daniel  Bernoulli  and  his  father  John  BernoulH.  The 
memoirs  of  both  are  contained  in  the  Recueil  des  pieces  qui  ont 
remporte  le  prix  de  VAcademie  Roy  ale  des  Sciences,  Tom.  3,  1734. 


DANIEL  BERNOULLI.  223 

A  French  translation  of  Daniel  Bernoulli's  memoir  occupies 
pages  95 — 122  of  the  volume  ;  the  original  memoir  in  Latin  occu- 
pies pages  125 — 144 

395.  The  portion  of  the  memoir  with  which  we  are  concerned 
occurs  at  the  beginning.  Daniel  Bernoulli  wishes  to  shew  that  we 
cannot  attribute  to  hazard  the  small  mutual  inclinations  of  the 
planetary  orbits.     He  puts  the  calculation  in  three  forms. 

(1)  He  finds  that  the  greatest  mutual  inclination  of  any  two 
planetary  orbits  is  that  of  Mercury  to  the  Ecliptic,  which  is  6°  54'. 
He  imagines  a  zone  of  the  breadth  of  6"  54'  on  the  surface  of  a 

sphere,  which  would  therefore  contain  about  —z  of  the  whole  sur- 
face of  the  sphere.  There  being  six  planets  altogether  he  takes 
|i^  for  the  chance  that  the  inclinations  of  five  of  the  planes  to  one 
plane  shall  all  be  less  than  6*^  54'. 

(2)  Suppose   however   that   all   the  planes  intersected  in  a 

common  line.     The  ratio  of  6°  54'  to  90°  is  equal  to  ^q  iiearly ; 

1 

and  he  takes  -r—n  for  the  chance  that  each  of  the  five  inclinations 
13^ 

would  be  less  than  6"  54'. 

(3)  Again ;  take  the  Sun  s  equator  as  the  plane  of  reference. 
The  greatest  inclination  of  the  plane  of  any  orbit  to  this  is  7°  30', 

which  is  about  r=-^  of  90" ;  and  he  takes  — r^  as  the  chance  that  each 
12  12*^ 

of  the  six  inclinations  would  be  less  than  7"  30'. 

896.     It  is  difficult  to  see  why  in  the  first  of  the  three  pre- 

1   .  2 

ceding  calculations  Daniel  Bernoulli  took  ^^  instead  of  — ;  that  is 

why  he  compared  his  zone  with  the  surface  of  a  sphere  instead  of 
with  the  surface  of  a  hemisphere.  It  would  seem  too  that  he 
should  rather  have  considered  the  poles  of  the  orbits  than  the 
planes  of  the  orbits,  and  have  found  the  chance  that  all  the 
other  poles  should  lie  within  a  given  distance  from  one  of  them. 


224  DANIEL   BERNOULLI. 

397.  We  shall  find  hereafter  that  D'  Alembert  did  not  admit 
that  there  was  any  value  in  Daniel  Bernoulli's  calculations. 

Laplace  proposes  to  find  the  probability  that  the  sum  of  all  the 
inclinations  should  not  exceed  an  assigned  quantity  ;  see  Theorie... 
des  Prob.  page  257.  The  principle  of  Daniel  Bernoulli's  attempt 
seems  more  natural,  because  it  takes  more  explicit  account  of  the 
fact  that  each  inclination  is  small. 

398.  The  next  memoir  by  Daniel  Bernoulli  is  entitled  Essai 
dune  nouvelle  analyse  de  la  mortalite  causee  par  la  petite  Verole, 
et  des  avantages  de  V Inocidation  pour  la  prevenir. 

This  memoir  is  contained  in  the  Hist  de  FA  cad. ...  Paris,  for 
1760  ;  the  date  of  publication  of  the  volume  is  1766  :  the  memoir 
occupies  pages  1 — 45  of  the  part  devoted  to  memoirs. 

399.  The  reading  of  the  memoir  commenced  on  April  30th, 
1760,  as  we  learn  from  its  seventh  page.  Before  the  memoir 
was  printed,  a  criticism  on  it  appeared,  which  Daniel  Bernoulli 
ascribes  to  a  grand  mathematicien ;  see  his  pages  4  and  18. 
In  consequence  of  this,  an  introduction  apologetique  was  written 
on  April  16th,  1765,  and  now  forms  the  first  six  pages  of  the 
whole. 

The  critic  was  D'Alembert;  see  Montucla,  page  426,  and 
our  Chapter  xiii. 

400.  Daniel  Bernoulli's  main  object  is  to  determine  the  mor- 
tality caused  by  the  small-pox  at  various  stages  of  age.  This  of 
course  could  have  been  determined  if  a  long  series  of  observations 
had  been  made ;  but  at  that  time  such  observations  had  not  been 
made.  Tables  of  mortality  had  been  formed,  but  they  gave  the 
total  number  of  deaths  at  various  ages  without  distinguishing 
the  causes  of  death.  Thus  it  required  calculation  to  determine 
the  result  which  Daniel  Bernoulli  was  seeking. 

401.  Daniel  Bernoulli  made  two  assumptions  :  that  in  a  year 
on  an  average  1  person  out  of  8  of  all  those  who  had  not  pre- 
viously taken  the  disease,  would  be  attacked  by  small-pox,  and 
that  1  out  of  every  8  attacked  would  die.  These  assumptions  he 
supported  by  appeal  to  observation  ;  but  they  might  not   be  uni- 


DANIEL   BERNOULLI.  225 

versally  admitted.  Since  the  introduction  of  vaccination,  the 
memoir  of  Bernoulli  will  have  no  practical  value ;  but  the  mathe- 
matical theory  which  he  based  on  his  hypotheses  is  of  sufficient 
interest  to  be  reproduced  here. 

402.  Let  X  denote  the  age  expressed  in  years  ;  let  f  denote 
the  number  who  survive  at  that  age  out  of  a  given  number 
who  were  born ;  let  s  denote  the  number  of  these  survivors  who 
have  not  had  the  small-pox.  Assume  that  in  a  year  the  small- 
pox attacks  1  out  of  every  n  who  have  not  had  the  disease, 
and  that  1  out  of  every  m  who  are  attacked  dies. 

The  number  of  survivors  who  have  not  had  the  small-pox 
continually  diminishes  ;  partly  because  the  small-pox  continually 
attacks  some  whom  it  had  previously  left  unattacked,  and  partly 
because  some  persons  die  of  other  diseases  without  ever  being 
attacked  by  the  small-pox. 

The   number  of  those  attacked  by  the  small-pox  during  the 

sdx 
element  dx  of  time   is  by  hypothesis  — -  :  because  we  suppose 

o  sdx 

-  to  be  attacked  in  one  year,  and  therefore  in  the  element 

n  n 

dx  of  a  year.     The  number  of  those  who  die  of  the  small-pox  is 

sdx 
by  hypothesis  ;  and  therefore  the  number  of  those  who  die 

^dx 
of  other  diseases  is  —  d^—  - —  .      But  this  last  number  must  be 

mn 

diminished   in  the  ratio  of  s  to  f,     because  we  only  want  the 

diminution  of  those  who  have  not  yet  had  the  small-pox,  of  whom 

the  number  is  s. 

Thus  „ds  =  —-i(d^-^--). 

n       g  V  7)inJ 

This  equation  is  to  be  integrated.     We  have 

s^dx 

• 

,        _  O..C        ..^^      ^..^       dx 

therefore 

mn 

15 


-  ds  ■• 

sdx 
n 

sd^- 

^ds 

^dx 

s' 

ns 

226 


DANIEL   BERNOULLI. 


Put  q  for  -  ;  thus,    da  =  — ^ dx  ; 

^  s  nin 


therefore 
therefore 

and 


n  log  {mq  —  l)—x-\-  constant ; 


^m^ 


s 


-1     =e^^^. 


m^ 


e  "   +  1 


To  determine  the  constant  C,  we  observe  that  when  x 
we  have  s  =  f ;  thus,  finally, 


=  0, 


s  = 


m^ 


(m  -  1)  ^'  +  1 


403.  By  this  formula  Daniel  Bernoulli  calculates  a  table  on 
the  basis  of  Halley's  table,  derived  from  the  Breslau  Observations, 
assuming  that  m  and  n  each  equal  8 ;  Halley's  table  gives  the 
values  of  f  corresponding  to  successive  integer  values  of  x,  and 
Daniel  Bernoulli's  formula  then  gives  the  values  of  s.  The  fol- 
lowing is  an  extract  from  the  table : 


X 

^ 

s 

0 

1300 

1300 

1 

1000 

896 

2 

855 

685 

3 

798 

571 

4 

760 

485 

5 

732 

416 

6 

710 

359 

7 

692 

311 

8 

680 

272 

9 

670 

237 

10 

661 

208 

11 

653 

182 

12 

646 

160 

13 

640 

140 

14 

634 

123 

15 

628 

108 

16 

622 

94 

DANIEL   BERNOULLI.  227 

Halley's  table  begins  with  1000  at  the  end  of  the  first  year, 
and  does  not  say  to  what  number  of  births  this  corresponds. 
Daniel  Bernoulli  gives  reasons  for  assuming  this  to  be  1300, 
which  accordingly  he  takes  ;  see  Art.  64?. 

404.  On  page  21  of  the  memoir,  Daniel  Bernoulli  says  that 
the  following  question  had  been  asked:  Of  all  persons  alive 
at  a  given  epoch  what  fractional  part  had  not  been  attacked 
by  the  small-pox  ?  The  inquirer  himself,  who  was  D'Alembert, 
estimated  the  number  at  one-fourth  at  most.  Daniel  Bernoulli 
himself  makes  it  about  two-thirteenths.  He  intimates  that  it 
would  be  desirable  to  test  this  by  observation.     He  adds, 

Voici  un  autre  theoreme  qui  pourroit  servir  h  la  verification  de 
nos  principes.  Si  de  tous  les  vivans  on  ne  prend  que  Tenfance  et  la 
jeunesse,  jusqu'a  I'age  de  seize  ans  et  demi,  on  trouvera  le  nombre 
de  ceux  qui  auront  eu  la  petite  verole  a  pea-pres  egal  au  nombre  de 
ceux  qui  ne  I'auront  pas  eue. 

405.  Daniel  Bernoulli  gives  another  interesting  investigation. 
Bequired  to  find  the  number  of  survivors  at  a  given  age  from 
a  given  number  of  births,  supposing  the  small-pox  altogether 
extinguished.  Retain  the  notation  of  Article  402 ;  and  let  z  be 
the  number  who  would  have  been  alive  at  the  age  x  if  there  had 
been  no  small-pox,  the  original  number  of  births  being  supposed 
the  same. 

The  whole  mortality  during   the  element  dx  of  time  being 

9  fix 
—  d^,  and  the  mortality  caused  by  the  small-pox  being  ,  we 

II  tit 

sd'Oc 
have  for  the  mortality  in  the  absence  of  small-pox  —  d^ . 

But  this  mortality  arises  from  a  population  f ;  and  we  must  mul- 
tiply it  by  g  to  obtain  the  mortality  which  would  arise  from  a 
population  z.     Hence,  finally, 


mn,> 

dz      d^     s    dx 

therefore  —  =  -p  -\r  -z.  —  • 

z        ^      g  tnn 

15—2 


228  DANIEL   BERNOULLI. 

Substitute  for  s  from  the  result  in  Art.  402  ;  then  integrate, 
and  determine  the  arbitrary  constant  by  the  condition  that  2=^ 
when  x  =  0.     Hence  we  shall  obtain 

z  me^ 


^      (m  -  1)  e"  +  1 
Thus  as  X  increases,  the  right-hand  member  approaches  the 


limit 


m  —  1 


406.  After  discussing  the  subject  of  the  mortality  caused  by 
the  small-pox,  Daniel  Bernoulli  proceeds  to  the  subject  of  In- 
oculation. He  admits  that  there  is  some  danger  in  Inoculation, 
but  finds  on  the  whole  that  it  is  attended  with  large  advantages. 
He  concluded  that  it  would  lengthen  the  average  dur^ation  of  life 
by  about  three  years.  This  was  the  part  of  the  memoir  which 
at  the  time  of  publication  would  be  of  the  greatest  practical 
importance ;  but  that  importance  happily  no  longer  exists. 

407.  We  shall  find  hereafter  that  DAlembert  strongly  ob- 
jected to  the  justness  of  Daniel  Bernoulli's  investigations.  La- 
place speaks  very  highly  of  Daniel  Bernoulli ;  Laplace  also  briefly 
indicates  the  method  of  treating  the  problem  respecting  Inocula- 
tion, but  as  he  does  not  assume  ?/^  and  w  to  be  constant,  he  rather 
follows  DAlembert  than  Daniel  Bernoulli;  see  Theoiie...des Proh., 
pages  cxxxvii.  and  413. 

408.  The  next  memoir  by  Daniel  Bernoulli  is  entitled  De  usu 
algoritlimi  infinitesimaUs  in  arte  conjectandl  specimen. 

This  memoir  is  contained  in  the  Novi  Comm...Petrop.  Vol.  xil, 
which  is  the  volume  for  the  years  17C6  and  1767 ;  the  date 
of  publication  of  the  volume  is  1768 ;  the  memoir  occupies 
pages  87 — 98. 

409.  The  object  of  the  memoir  is  twofold.  A  certain  problem 
in  chances  is  to  be  solved,  which  is  wanted  in  the  next  memoir  to 
which  we  shall  come ;  and  the  introduction  of  the  Differential 
Calculus  into  the  Theory  of  Probability  is  to  be  illustrated.  The 
reader  will  see  in  Art.  402  that  Daniel  Bernoulli  had  already  really 


DANIEL   BERXOULLI.  229 

employed  the  Differential  Calculus,  and  the  present  memoir  con- 
tains remarks  which  would  serve  to  explain  the  process  of  Art.  402 ; 
but  the  remarks  are  such  as  any  student  could  easily  supply 
for  himself  We  shall  see  the  point  illustrated  in  another  memoir. 
See  Art.  417. 

410.  The  problem  which  Daniel  Bernoulli  solves  is  in  its 
simplest  form  as  follows  :  In  a  bag  are  2n  cards  ;  two  of  them  are 
marked  1,  two  of  them  are  marked  2,  two  of  them  are  marked  3, ... 
and  so  on.  We  draw  out  m  cards ;  required  the  probable  number 
oi pairs  which  remain  in  the  bag. 

We  give  the  solution  of  Daniel  Bernoulli  with  some  changes  of 
notation.  Suppose  that  a?,,,  pairs  remain  after  m  cards  have  been 
drawn  out ;  let  a  new  drawing  be  made.  The  card  thus  drawn  out 
is  either  one  of  the  cards  of  a  pair,  or  it  is  not ;  the  probabilities 
for  these  two  cases  are  proportional  to  20?,,^,  and  2n  —  2x,,^  —  m  re- 
spectively :  in  the  former  case  there  remain  x^^  —  1  pairs  in  the  bag, 
and  in  the  latter  case  there  remain  x,^  pairs.  Thus  by  ordinary 
principles 

^  ^^m  G^.,  -  1)  +  (2>i  -  2^,^  -  m)  x^ 
"^1  2/1  -  m 


2n  —  m—  2 


Zn  —  m 


iC„j 


We  can  thus  form  in  succession  x^,  x^,  ^3>  •••      As  x^=n  we 
find  that 

(2)1  —  on)  (2n  -  m  —  1) 


•^ni  "~ 


2  {2n  - 1) 

411.  The  problem  is  extended  by  Daniel  Bernoulli  afterwards 
to  a  greater  generality  ;  but  we  have  given  sufficient  to  enable  the 
reader  to  understand  the  nature  of  the  present  memoir,  and  of  that 
to  which  we  now  proceed. 

412.  The  next  memoir  is  entitled  De  duratione  media  matri- 
moniorum,  pro  qitacunque  conjugum  aetate,  aliisque  quaestionihus 
affinibus. 

This  memoir  is  closely  connected  with  the  preceding ;  it  fol- 
lows in  the  same  volume  of  the  JS'ovi  Comm...Petrop.,  and  occupies 
pages  99—126. 


230  DANIEL  BERNOULLI. 

413.  Suppose  500  men  of  a  given  age,  as  for  example  20  years, 
to  marry  500  women  of  the  same  age.  The  tables  of  mortality 
will  shew  at  what  rate  these  1000  individuals  gradually  diminish 
annually  until  all  are  dead.  But  these  tables  do  not  distinguish 
the  married  from  the  unmarried,  so  that  we  cannot  learn  from  them 
the  number  of  unbroken  couples  after  the  lapse  of  a  given  number 
of  years.  Daniel  Bernoulli  applies  the  result  of  Art.  410  ;  the  pairs 
of  cards  correspond  to  the  married  couples.  From  that  article 
knowing-  the  number  of  cards  which  remain  undrawn  we  infer  the 
probable  number  of  pairs.  The  number  of  cards  remaining  un- 
drawn corresponds  to  the  number  of  persons  remaining  alive  at  a 
given  age  ;  this  is  taken  from  the  tables  of  mortality,  and  by  the 
formula  the  probable  number  of  unbroken  couples  is  calculated. 
Daniel  Bernoulli  calculates  such  a  table  for  the  numbers  we  have 
supposed  above. 

414.  Daniel  Bernoulli  then  proceeds  to  the  case  in  which  the 
husband  and  wife  are  supposed  of  different  ages  ;  this  requires  the 
extended  problem  to  which  we  have  referred  in  Art.  411.  Daniel 
Bernoulli  calculates  a  table  for  the  case  in  which  500  men  aged 
40  years  marry  500  women  aged  20  years. 

Daniel  Bernoulli  allows  that  his  results  must  not  claim  im- 
plicit confidence.  He  has  taken  the  same  laws  of  mortality  for 
both  men  and  women,  though  of  course  he  was  aware  that  on  an 
average  women  live  longer  than  men.  With  respect  to  this  fact  he 
says,  page  100,  ...neque  id  diversse  vivendi  rationi  tribui  potest, 
quia  ista  sequioris  sexus  praerogativa  a  primis  incunabilis  constan- 
tissime  manifestatur  atque  per  totam  vitam  in  illo  manet. 

Daniel  Bernoulli's  process  is  criticised  by  Trembley  in  the 
M^moires  de  V Acad.... Berlin,  1799,  1800. 

The  problem  respecting  the  mean  duration  of  marriages  is  con- 
sidered by  Laplace,  Theorie...des  Proh.  page  415. 

415.  The  memoir  which  we  have  noticed  in  Arts.  412 — 414 
bears  a  close  analogy  to  the  memoir  which  we  have  noticed  in 
Arts.  398 — 406.  In  both  cases  theory  is  employed  to  supply  the 
lack  of  observations,  in  both  cases  the  questions  discussed  are  of  the 
same  kind,  and  in  both  cases  the  use  of  the  Differential  Calculus  is 
illustrated. 


DANIEL   BERNOULLI.  231 

416.  The  next  memoir  by  Daniel  Bernoulli  is  entitled  Dis- 
quisitiones  Analyticce  de  novo  prohlemate  conjectwrali. 

This  memoir  is  contained  in  the  Novi  Comm...Petrop...Yo\.  14, 
1769,  pars  prior.  The  date  1759  occurs  by  mistake  in  the  title- 
page.  The  date  of  publication  of  the  volume  is  1770.  The 
memoir  occupies  pages  1 — 25  of  the  part  devoted  to  memoirs. 

417.  The  object  of  the  memoir  is  to  illustrate  the  use  of  the 
Differential  Calculus,  and  it  is  thus  analogous  to  memoirs  which  we 
have  already  noticed  by  Daniel  Bernoulli. 

Suppose  three  urns  ;  in  the  first  are  n  white  balls,  in  the  second 
n  black  balls,  in  the  third  n  red  balls.  A  ball  is  taken  at  random 
from  each  urn ;  the  ball  taken  from  the  first  urn  is  put  into  the 
second,  the  ball  taken  from  the  second  is  put  into  the  third,  and 
the  ball  taken  from  the  third  is  put  into  the  first ;  this  operation 
is  repeated  for  any  assigned  number  of  times :  required  the  proba- 
ble distribution  of  the  balls  at  the  end  of  these  operations. 

Suppose  that  after  x  operations  the  probable  numbers  of  white 
balls  in  the  three  urns  are  denoted  by  u^.,  v^y  w^  respectively.    Then 

1t/~.,t  —  U,f  ~~         ~1  • 

"'■^^       "^      n       n 
For  —  is  the  probability  of  drawing  one  white  ball  out  of  the 


n 


10 


first  urn,  and  -^  is  the  probability  that  a  white  ball  will  be  drawn 


n 


from  the  third  urn  and  so  put  into  the  first.     Similarly 

By  eliminating,  using  the  condition  u^-\-v^-\-w^=  n,  we  may 
obtain  an  equation  in  Finite  Differences  of  the  second  order  for 

Ujc,  namely, 

/^     3\  /^      3      3\      1 

'^x^'i  =  "^^ar+l  (2. ]  —f^'x       1 H— )+-• 

x+2  x+i  \^  ^J  X   \^  ^^         ^^y         ^ 

But  the  following  process  is  more  symmetrical.    Put  w^^^  =  Eu^, 
and  separate  the  symbols  in  the  usual  way ; 


232  DANIEL   BERNOULLI. 


thus       •i^-(^-D^'^"^''^' 


E-(l--]  [  v^  =  -  u^, 


n    I  n 


{ 


^_(1__)  [^^=      ^;^, 


n  n 


therefore  \  E-  (  1  -  -  )  \  u^^iAux- 


nj  I     ^     \nj 


Therefore   w,  =  ^  f  1  -  -  +  -)\  ^  f  1  -  -  +  -)V  (7  fl  -  -  +  '^V, 

\        n      nJ  \        n     nJ  \        n     nj 

where  A,  B,  C  are  constants,  and  a,  A  7  ^^^  the  three  cube  roots 
of  unity. 

Then  from  the  above  equations  we  obtain 

therefore 

\        n     nJ  \        71     7iJ  \        n     nJ 

Similarly 

\        n     nJ  \        n      nJ  \        n     nJ 

The  three  constants  A,  B,  C  are  not  all  arbitrary,  for  we 
require  that 

with  this  condition  and  the  facts  that 

Uo  =  n,    ^0  =  0,    Wq=0, 

we  shall  obtain  A  =  B=  G=-^. 

418.  The  above  process  will  be  seen  to  be  applicable  if  the 
number  of  urns  be  any  whatever,  instead  of  being  limited  to  three. 

We  need  not  investigate  the  distribution  of  the  balls  of  the 
other  colours  ;  for  it  is  evident  from  symmetry  that  at  the  end  of  x 


DANIEL  BERNOULLI.  233 

Operations  the  black  balls  will  be  probably  distributed  thus,  ii^  in 
the  second  urn,  v^  in  the  third,  and  ic^  in  the  first ;  similarly  the 
red  balls  will  be  probably  distributed  thus,  ii^  in  the  third  urn,  v^  in 
the  first,  and  w^  in  the  second. 

It  should  be  observed  that  the  equations  in  Finite  Differences 
and  the  solution  will  be  the  same  whatever  be  the  original  distri- 
bution of  the  balls,  supposing  that  there  were  originally  n  in  each 
urn ;  the  only  difference  will  be  in  the  values  to  be  assigned  to  the 
arbitrary  constants.  Nor  does  the  process  require  n  white  balls 
originally.  Thus  in  fact  we  solve  the  following  problem  :  Suppose 
a  given  number  of  urns,  each  containing  n  balls,  m  of  the  Avhole 
number  of  balls  are  white  and  the  rest  not  white  ;  the  original 
distribution  of  the  white  balls  is  given :  required  their  probable 
distribution  after  x  operations. 

419.  Daniel  Bernoulli  does  not  give  the  investigation  which 
we  have  given  in  Art.  417.  He  simply  indicates  the  following 
result,  which  he  probably  obtained  by  induction  : 


3 


together  with  similar  expressions  for  v^  and  w^.  These  can  be 
obtained  by  expanding  by  the  Binomial  Theorem  the  expressions 
we  have  given,  using  the  known  values  of  the  sums  of  the  powers 
of  a,  P,  y. 

420.  Now  a  problem  involving  the  Differential  Calculus  can 
be  framed,  exactly  similar  to  this  problem  of  the  urns.  Suppose 
three  equal  vessels,  the  first  filled  with  a  white  fluid,  the  second 
with  a  black  fluid,  and  the  third  with  a  red  fluid.  Let  there  be 
very  small  tubes  of  equal  bore,  which  allow  fluid  to  pass  from  the 
first  vessel  into  the  second,  from  the  second  into  the  third,  and  from 
the  third  into  the  first.  Suppose  that  the  fluids  have  the  property 
of  mixing  instantaneously  and  completely.  Required  at  the  end 
of  the  time  t  the  distribution  of  the  fluids  in  the  vessels. 


23  i  DANIEL   BERNOULLI. 

Suppose  at  the  end  of  the  time  t  the  quantities  of  the  white 
fluid  in  the  three  vessels  to  be  u,  v,  w  respectively.  We  obtain  the 
following  equations, 

du  =  kdt  (w  —  y), 

dv  =  kdt  (u  —  v), 
dw  —  kdt  {v  —  w)y 
where  Zj  is  a  constant. 

Daniel  Bernoulli  integrates  these  equations,  by  an  unsym- 
metrical  and  difficult  process.     They  may  be  easily  integrated  by 

the  modern  method  of  separating  the  symbols.    Put  i)  for  -7- ;  thus 

at 

{D  +  ^)  w  =  kw,    (J)  ■\-k)  v=  kuj    (I)-\-k)w  =  kv, 

therefore  (D  -\-Tcf  u  =  Hu. 

Hence  u  =  e"^*  [Ad"^  +  Be""^'  +  Ce^*^'}, 

where  A,  B,  G  are  arbitrary  constants,  and  a,  /3,  7  are  the  three  cube 
roots  of  unity.  The  values  of  v  and  w  can  be  deduced  from  that  of 
u.     Let  us  suppose  that  initially  u  —  h,  v  =  0,  i^  =  0 ;  we  shall  find 

that  A  =B=  C=^,  so  that 

o 

Laplace  has  given  the  result  for  any  number  of  vessels  in  the 
Theorie...des  Proh.  page  303. 

421.  Now  it  is  Daniel  Bernoulli's  object  to  shew,  that  when  x 
and  n  are  supposed  indefinitely  large  in  the  former  problem  its 
results  correspond  with  those  of  the  present  problem.  Here  indeed 
we  do  not  gain  any  thing  by  this  fact,  because  we  can  solve  the 
former  problem  ;  but  if  the  former  problem  had  been  too  difficult 
to  solve  we  might  have  substituted  the  latter  problem  for  it.  And 
thus  generally  Daniel  Bernoulli's  notion  is  that  we  may  often  ad- 
vantageously change  a  problem  of  the  former  kind  into  one  of  the 
latter  kind. 

If  we  suppose  n  and  x  very  large  we  can  obtain  by  the  Bino- 
mial Theorem,  or  by  the  Logarithmic  Theorem, 


DANIEL   BERNOULLI.  235 


( 


1  -  -     =  e  '* 
n 


Hence  when  n  and  x  are  very  large,  we  find  that  the  value  of  u^ 
ofiven  in  Art.  419  reduces  to 


«e-"U  +  ,4-f-T+7^l'-U...^ 


6 

13   \nj    '  16  V**> 

Daniel  Bernoulli  sums  the  series  in  the  brackets  by  the  aid  of 
the  Integral  Calculus.  We  know  however  by  the  aid  of  the 
theorem  relating  to  the  value  of  the  sums  of  the  powers  of 
a,  A  7,  that  this  series  is  equal  to 

Hence  the  analogy  of  the  value  of  u^,  when  x  and  n  are  in- 
definitely large,  with  the  value  of  u  in  Art.  420  is  sufficiently 
obvious. 

Daniel  Bernoulli  gives  some  numerical  applications  of  his 
general  results. 

Daniel  Bernoulli's  memoir  has  been  criticised  by  Malfatti,  in 
the  Meniorie  ...  della  Societa  Italiana,  Vol.  I.  1782. 

422.  The  next  memoir  by  Daniel  Bernoulli  is  entitled,  2Ien- 
sura  Sortis  ad  fortuitam  successionem  rerum  naturaliter  contin- 
gentium  applicata.  This  memoir  is  in  the  same  volume  of  the 
I^ovi  Comm Petrop.  as  the  preceding;  it  occupies  pages  26 — 45. 

423.  The  memoir  begins  by  noticing  the  near  equality  in  the 
numbers  of  boys  and  girls  who  are  born  ;  and  proposes  to  consider 
whether  this  is  due  to  chance.  In  the  present  memoir  only  thus 
much  is  discussed  :  assuming  that  the  births  of  a  boy  and  of  a  girl 
are  equally  likely,  find  the  probability  that  out  of  a  given 
number  of  births,  the  boys  shall  not  deviate  from  the  half  by 
more  or  less  than  a  given  number.  The  memoir  gives  some  calcu- 
lations and  some  numerical  examples. 

Daniel  Bernoulli  seems  very  strangely  to  be  unaware  that 
all  which  he  effects  had  been  done  better  by  Stirling  and  Do 
Moivre  long  before ;  see  De  Moivre's  Doctrine  of  Chances^ 
pages  243—254. 


236  DANIEL   BERNOULLI. 

The  following  is  all  that  Daniel  BeiTioulli  contributes  to  the 
theory.     Let  m  and  n  be  lai-ge  numbers  ;  let 

|2n      1 


u  = 


V  = 


2m     1 


in  f 


He  shews  that  approximately 


II  /^m-\- 1 


V      V  4w  +  1  * 

/I      IN"" 
He  also  states  the  following :    in  the  expansion  of  f  ^  +  „  I 

the  jj}'^  term  from   the   middle   is  approximately  equal  to    —2  . 

These  results  are  included  in  those  of  Stirling  and  De  Moivre, 
so  that  Daniel  Bernoulli's  memoir  was  useless  when  it  appeared; 
see  Art.  837. 

424.  The  next  memoir  by  Daniel  Bernoulli  is  entitled  Di- 
judicatio  maxime  prohabilis  plurium  ohservationum  discrepantitwi 
Clique  verisimillima  inductio  inde  formanda.  This  memoir  is  con- 
tained in  the  Acta  Acad.  ...Petrop.  for  1777,  pay^s  piHor ;  the 
date  of  publication  of  the  volume  is  1778  :  the  memoir  occupies 
pages  8 — 23  of  the  part  devoted  to  memoirs. 

425.  The  memoir  is  not  the  first  which  treated  of  the  errors 
of  observations  as  a  branch  of  the  Theory  of  Probability,  for 
Thomas  Simpson  and  Lagrange  had  already  considered  the  sub- 
ject ;  see  Art.  371. 

Daniel  Bernoulli  however  does  not  seem  to  have  been  ac- 
quainted with  the  researches  of  his  predecessors. 

Daniel  Bernoulli  says  that  the  common  method  of  obtaining 
a  result  from  discordant  observations,  is  to  take  the  arithmetical 
mean  of  the  result.  This  amounts  to  supposing  all  the  observa- 
tions of  equal  weight.  Daniel  Bernoulli  objects  to  this  supposition, 
and  considers  that  small  errors  are  more  probable  than  large 
errors.  Let  e  denote  an  error ;  he  proposes  to  measure  the  pro- 
bability of  the   error  by  ^(j-'^  —  e^),  where  7-  is  a  constant.     Then 


DANIEL   BERNOULLI.  237 

the  best  result  from  a  number  of  observations  will  be  that 
which  makes  the  product  of  the  probabilities  of  all  the  errors 
a  maximum.  Thus,  suppose  that  observations  have  given  the 
values  a,h,  c,  ...  for  an  element ;  denote  the  true  value  bv  x ; 
then  we  have  to  find  x  so  that  the  following  product  may  be  a 
maximum  : 

^y-  _  (^  _  ay]  sjy  -{x-  hy]  s/y  -{x-  cy] . . . 

Daniel  Bernoulli  gives  directions  as  to  the  value  to  be  assigned 
to  the  constant  ?\ 

426.  Thus  Daniel  Bernoulli  agrees  in  some  respects  with 
modern  theory.  The  chief  difference  is  that  modern  theory  takes 
for  the  curve  of  probability  that  defined  by  the  equation 

while  Daniel  Bernoulli  takes  a  circle. 

Daniel  Bernoulli  gives  some  good  remarks  on  the  subject ; 
and  he  illustrates  his  memoir  by  various  numerical  examples, 
which  however  are  of  little  interest,  because  they  are  not  derived 
from  real  observations.  It  is  a  fatal  objection  to  his  method,  even 
if  no  other  existed,  that  as  soon  as  the  number  of  observations 
surpasses  two,  the  equation  from  which  the  unknown  quantity  is 
to  be  found  rises  to  an  unmanageable  degree.  This  objection  he 
himself  recognises. 

427.  Daniel  Bernoulli's  memoir  is  followed  by  some  remarks 
by  Euler,  entitled  Ohservationes  in  pj'aecedeiitem  dissertationem ; 
these  occupy  pages  24 — 33  of  the  volume. 

Euler  considers  that  Daniel  Bernoulli  was  quite  arbitrary  in 
proposing  to  make  the  product  of  the  probabilities  of  the  errors 
a  maximum.  Euler  proposes  another  method,  which  amounts  to 
making  the  sum  of  the  fourth  powers  of  the  probabilities  a 
maximum,  that  is,  with  the  notation  of  Art.  425, 

y  _  (a:  -  ayY  +  [r'  -  {x  -  ly]'  4- 17-^  -{x-  c)^  +  . . . 
is  to  be  a  maximum.     Euler  sa3^s  it  is  to  be  a  maximum,  but 


288  DANIEL  BERNOULLI. 

he  does  not  discriminate  between  a  maximum  and  a  minimum. 
The  equation  which  is  obtained  for  determining  iK  is  a  cubic, 
and  thus  it  is  conceivable  that  there  may  be  two  minima  values 
and  one  maximum,  or  only  one  minimum  and  no  maximum. 

Euler  seems  to  have  objected  to  the  wrong  part  of  Daniel 
Bernoulli's  method  ;  the  particular  law  of  probability  is  really  the 
arbitrary  part,  the  principle  of  making  the  product  of  the  pro- 
babilities a  maximum  is  suggested  by  the  Theory  of  Probability. 

Euler  illustrates  his  method  by  an  example  derived  from  real 
observations. 


CHAPTER   XII. 


EULER, 

428.  EULER  was  bora  in  1707,  and  died  in  1783.  His 
industry  and  genius  have  left  permanent  impressions  in  every 
field  of  mathematics ;  and  although  his  contributions  to  the 
Theory  of  Probability  relate  to  subjects  of  comparatively  small 
importance,  yet  they  will  be  found  not  unworthy  of  his  own  great 
powers  and  fame. 

429.  Euler's  first  memoir  is  entitled  Calcul  de  la  Prohahilite 
dans  le  Jeu  de  Rencontre.  This  memoir  is  published  in  the  volume 
for  1751  of  the  Histoire  de  V Acad ...  Berlin ;  the  date  of  pub- 
lication is  1753 :  the  memoir  occupies  pages  255 — 270  of  the 
volume. 

430.  The  problem  discussed  is  that  which  is  called  the  game 
of  Treize,  by  Montmort  and  Nicolas  Bernoulli-;  see  Art.  162. 
Euler  proceeds  in  a  way  which  is  very  common  with  him ;  he 
supposes  first  one  card,  then  two  cards,  then  three,  then  four,  and 
exhibits  definitely  the  various  cases  which  may  occur.  After- 
wards, by  an  undemonstrated  inductive  process,  he  arrives  at  the 
general  law. 

The  results  obtained  by  Euler  had  been  given  more  briefly 
and  simply  by  Nicolas  Bernoulli,  and  published  by  Montmort  in 
his  page  301 ;  so  we  must  conclude  that  Euler  had  not  read 
Montmort's  book. 

When  n  is  infinite,  the  expression  given  in  Art.  161  for  the 


240  EULER. 

chance  that  at  least  one  card  is  in  its  right  place  becomes  equal 
to  1  —  e~\  where  e  is  the  base  of  the  Napierian  logarithms  ;  this  is 
noticed  by  Euler  :  see  also  Art.  287. 

431.  The  next  memoir  by  Euler  is  entitled  Recherches  g^ne- 
rales  sur  la  mortalite  et  la  multiplication  du  genre  humain.  This 
memoir  is  published  in  the  volume  for  1760  of  the  Histoire  de 
V Acad.  ...  Berlin ;  the  date  of  publication  is  1767:  the  memoir 
occupies  pages  144 — 164. 

432.  The  memoir  contains  some  simple  theorems  concerning 
the  mortality  and  the  increase  of  mankind.  Suppose  N  infants 
born  at  the  same  time ;  then  Euler  denotes  by  (1)  N  the  number 
of  them  alive  at  the  end  of  one  year,  by  (2)  N  the  number  of 
them  alive  at  the  end  of  two  years,  and  so  on. 

Then  he  considers  some  ordinary  questions.  For  example, 
a  certain  number  of  men  are  alive,  all  aged  m  years,  how  many 
of  them  will  probably  be  alive  at  the  end  of  n  years  ? 

According  to  Euler's  notation,  (m)  N  represents  the  number 
alive  aged  m  years  out  of  an  original  number  N\  and  {m  +  n)  N 
represents  the  number  of  those  who  are  alive  at  the  end  of  n 

more  years ;  so  that    — ,    .         is    the   fraction    of  the    number 

aged  m  years  who  will  probably  be  alive  at  the  end  of  n  years. 
Thus,  if  we  have  a  number  M  at  present  aged  m  years,  there  will 

probably  be  — -. — —-  M  of  them  alive  at  the  end  of  n  years. 

433.  Then  Euler  gives  formulae  for  annuities  on  a  life.  Sup- 
pose M  persons,  at  present  each  aged  m  years,  and  that  each 
of  them  pays  down  the   sum   a,   for  which  he  is   to  receive  x 

1 

annually  as  long  as  he  lives.     Let  -  be  the  present  worth  of  the 

unit  of  money  due  at  the  end  of  one  year. 

(m  -f  1) 
Then  at  the  end  of  a  year  there  will  be  M  '       .   ^   of  the 

(in) 

persons  alive,  each  of  whom  is  to  receive  x :  therefore  the  present 

worth  of  the  whole  sum  to  be  received  is  -  M  —- -r — . 

X  {m) 


EULEE.  241 

Similarly,   at    the   end   of   the    second    year    there    will   be 

(?/i  +  2) 
M  —7 — -^  of  the  persons  alive,  each    of   whom  is  to  receive  x : 

(w) 

therefore  the  present  worth  of  the  whole  sum  to  be  received  is 
-5  M  ^  ,   .      .    And  so  on. 

The  present  worth  of  all  the  sums  to  be  received  ought  to  be 
equal  to  Ma  ;  hence  dividing  by  M  we  get 

_    X     ((m  +  1)      (m  +  2)      (m  +  3) 

Euler  gives  a  numerical  table  of  the  values  of  (1),  (2),  ...  (95), 
which  he  says  is  deduced  from  the  observations  of  Kerseboom. 

434.  Let  iV  denote  the  number  of  infants  born  in  one  year, 
and  r'i\^  the  number  born  in  the  next  year ;  then  we  may  suppose 
that  the  same  causes  which  have  changed  N"  into  riV  will  change 
rN  into  rW,  so  that  r^N  will  be  the  number  born  in  the  year 
succeeding  that  in  which  rN  were  born.  Similarly,  r^N  will  be 
born  in  the  next  succeeding  year,  and  so  on.  Let  us  now  express 
the  number  of  the  population  at  the  end  of  100  years. 

Out  of  the  N  infants  born  in  the  present  year,  there  will 
be  (100)  N  alive  ;  out  of  the  rN  born  in  the  next  year,  there  will 
be  (99)  rN  alive  ;  and  so  on.  Thus  the  whole  number  of  persons 
alive  at  the  end  of  100  years  will  be 


[  ^.         ^.  ^ 


Therefore  the  ratio  of  the  population  in  the  100*''  year  to  the 
number  of  infants  born  in  that  year  will  be 

If  we  assume  that  the  ratio  of  the  population  in  any  year  to  the 
number  of  infants  born  in  that  year  is  constant,  and  we  know  this 
ratio  for  any  year,  we  may  equate  it  to  the  expression  just  given  : 
then  since  (1),  (2),  (3),  ...  are  known  by  observation,  we  have 
an  equation  for  finding  r. 

16 


212  EULEn. 

435.  A  memoir  by  Euler,  entitled  Stir  les  Rentes  Viageres, 
immediately  follows  tlie  preceding,  occupying  pages  1G5 — 175  of 
the  volume. 

Its  principal  point  is  a  formula  for  facilitating  tlie  calculation 
of  a  life  annuity. 

Let  A.,^^  denote  the  value  of  an  annuity  of  one  pound  on  the 
life  of  a  person  aged  7n  years,  A,^_^^  the  value  of  an  annuity  of 
one  pound  on  the  life  of  a  person  aged  m  +  1  years.  Then  by 
the  preceding  memoir,  Art.  433, 

1     {{m-^l)       0)^  +  2)       U+3)  I 

.       _    _1 {{m^      (m  +  3)       (»z  +  4)  ] 

"'^^      (m+1)    1       \       ^       X'    "^       \'       "^  ""J  ' 


therefore  (m)  X  A,,,  =  [m  +  1)  +  {m  +  1)  J, 


Wi+l" 


Thus  when  A.^^  has  been  calculated,  Ave  can  calculate  A„^^^ 
easily. 

Euler  gives  a  table  exhibiting  the  value  of  an  annuity  on 
any  age  from  0  to  94.  But  with  respect  to  the  ages  90,  91,  92, 
93,  94,  he  says, 

Mais  je  ne  voudrois  pas  consei'der  a  un  entrepreneur  de  se  mekr 
avec  de  tels  vieillards,  a  nioins  que  leur  nombre  ne  fut  assez  consider- 
able; ce  qui  est  une  regie  generale  pour  tons  les  etablissemens  fondes 
sur  les  probabilites. 

Euler  is  of  opinion  that  the  temptations  do  not  appear  suf- 
ficient to  induce  many  persons  to  buy  annuities  on  terms  which 
would  be  advantageous  to  the  sellers.  He  suggests  that  defended 
annuities  might  perhaps  be  more  successful ;  for  it  follows  from 
his  calculations,  that  350  crowns  should  purchase  for  a  new  born 
infant  an  annuity  of  100  crowns  to  commence  at  the  age  of 
20  years,  and  continue  for  life.     He  adds, 

...et  si  I'on  y  vouloit  employer  la  somme  de  3500  ecus,  ce  seroit 
toujours  un  bel  etablissement,  que  de  jouir  cles  I'age  de  20  ans  d'une 
pension  fixe  de  1000  ecus.  Ce^^endant  il  est  encore  douteux,  s'il  se 
trouveroit  plusieurs  parens  qui  voiuh"oicnt  bien  faiie  uu  tel  sacrifice 
pour  le  lien  de  leurs  enfans. 


EULER.  2i3 

436.  The  next  memoir  by  Euler  is  entitled  Sur  Vavantage  du 
Banqiiier  cm  jeu  de  Fharaon.  This  memoir  was  published  in  the 
volume  for  1764  of  the  Histoire  de  V Acad.... Berlin;  the  date  of 
publication  is  1766  :  the  memoir  occupies  pages  144 — 164. 

437.  Euler  merely  solves  the  same  problem  as  had  been 
solved  by  Montmort  and  Nicolas  Bernoulli,  but  he  makes  no  refer- 
ence to  them  or  any  other  writer.  He  gives  a  new  form  hoAvever 
to  the  result  which  we  will  notice. 

Consider  the  equation  in  Finite  Differences, 

m  {in  —  1)      (;?  —  m)  (n  —  ??2  —  1 ) 
^'"  "  2n  (ii  -  1)  ^  71  (n  -  1)  ""-'  • 

By  successive  substitution  we  obtain 

m  (m  —  1)S 


u„  = 


"     2n{?i-l){n-2)  ...  (n-m  +  1)' 

where  S  denotes  the  sum  (f)  (u)  +  </>  (?i  —  2)  +  (^  (/i  —  4)  +  . . .  , 

(f>  (>i)  being  (ii  —  2)  (n  —  S)  ...  (n  —  m  +  1). 

This  coincides  with  what  we  have  given  in  Art.  155,  supposing 
that  for  A  we  put  unity. 

AYe  shall  first  find  a  convenient  expression  for  S.     We  see  that 

^=  coefficient  of  x"'~^  in  the  expansion  of  (1  +£c)"~^ 


m 


Hence  S  is  equal  to  |  m  —  2  times  the  coefficient  of  cc'"  "  in  the 
expansion  of 

(1 + xy-' + (1  +  xy-'  +(14-  xy-"  +  .,. 

Now  in  the  game  of  Pharaon  we  have  n  always  even ;  thus  we 
may  suppose  the  series  to  be  continued  down  to  1,  and  then  its 
sum  is 

(i+^)"-i  ^,  . .  (1+^r-i 

(1  -\-'xy^l  ^^'""^  ''      2x  +  x'     ' 
Thus  we  require  the  coefficient  of  x"'"^  in  the  expansion  of 

(1  +  xy  - 1 

2-^x       ' 

16— 2 


2H  EULER. 

This  coefficient  is 

n{n-l)  ...  {n-m-\-  2)      n  {n  -  1)  ...  (n-m  +  3) 

2  1  on  -  1  ~  4  I  ?/z  -  2 


n  (n  —  1)  ...  {n  —  m-\-  4) 
■^  8  !  m  -  3 


Then  8  —  \m  —  2  times  this  coefficient. 
Hence  with  this  expression  for  S  we  find  that 

1  772  1  771  {m  —  1) 


^i'n    =    T 


'"     4  7i  -  «i  +  1      8  (n  -  ??i  +  1)  {n  -  ??z  +  2) 

1  m  {in  —  1)  (w  —  2) 

IG   (?i  -  wi  +  1)  {n  -  m  +  2)  («  -  m  +  3) 


+ 


.   (_  1 V^  -1         m(m-l)...2 
■^^       ^    2"^  (yi-m  +  1)  ...(vi-1)'    • 

This  is  the  expression  for  the  advantage  of  the  Banker  which 
was  given  by  Nicolas  Bernoulli,  and  to  which  we  have  referred  in 
Art.  157. 

Now  the  form  which  Euler  gives  for  w„  is 

m   {    m  —  1  {m  —  l){m  —  2){m  —  2) 


2'"  \  l{n-l)  1.2.3(/i-3) 

•  •  •    (    • 


{m  —  1)  {m  —  2)  {m  —  3)  (m  —  4)  {m  —  5) 
+ ^^ — ^    o    A — ^7 ^^ i- 


1.2. 3. 4. 5(;z-5) 

Euler  obtained  this  formula  by  trial  from  the  cases  in  which 
w  =  2,  3,  4,  . . .  8  ;  but  he  gives  no  general  demonstration.  We  will 
deduce  it  from  Nicolas  Bernoulli's  formula. 

By  the  theory  of  partial  fractions  we  can  decompose  the 
terms  in  Nicolas  Bernoulli's  formula,  and  thus  obtain  a  series  of 
fractions  having  for  denominators  w  —  1,  w  —  2,  n  —  3,  . . .  ?z  —  ?7i  +  1  ; 
and  the  numerators  will  be  independent  of  n. 

We  will  find  the  numerator  of  the  fraction  whose  denominator 
is  w  —  r. 

From  the  last  term  in  Nicolas  Bernoulli's  formula  we  obtain 

{-ly^^     w(m-l)...2 


m  —  ^  —  r    ?'  —  1  ' 


EULER.  245 


from  the  last  term  but  one  we  obtain 


2"'"'     \m-l-r\r-2' 


and  proceeding  in  this  way  we  find  for  the  sum 

_1    m-l-r  |^~TT2  "^^       17273        ''+-"j 


a^ir 


2»'+i  1^ 


(- 1)''""  I  m 

-^ 1  -  (1  -  2)'    . 

n  —  1  —  r    I  ) 


This  vanishes  if  r  be  an  et;e?i  number ;   and  is  equal  to 


'2r\r  \m-l-r' 
if  r  be  odd. 

Thus  Euler's  formula  follows  from  Nicolas  Bernoulli's. 

438.  The  next  memoir  by  Euler  is  entitled  Sur  la  prohabilite 
des  sequences  dans  la  Lotterie  Genoise.  This  memoir  was  published 
in  the  volume  for  1765  of  the  Histoire  de  V Acad.... Berlin;  the 
date  of  publication  is  1767;  the  memoir  occupies  pages  191 — 230. 

439.  In  the  lottery  here  considered  90  tickets  are  numbered 
consecutively  from  1  to  90,  and  5  tickets  are  drawn  at  random. 
The  question  may  be  asked,  what  is  the  chance  that  two  or 
more  consecutive  numbers  should  occur  in  the  drawings?  Such 
a  result  is  called  a  sequence ;  thus,  for  example,  if  the  numbers 
drawn  are  4,  5,  6,  27,  28,  there  is  a  sequence  of  three  and  also  a 
sequence  of  two.  Euler  considers  the  question  generally.  He 
supposes  that  there  are  n  tickets  numbered  consecutively  from  1  to 
n,  and  he  determines  the  chance  of  a  sequence,  if  two  tickets  are 
drawn,  or  if  three  tickets  are  drawn,  and  so  on,  up  to  the  case  in 
which  six  tickets  are  drawn.  And  having  successively  investigated 
all  these  cases  he  is  able  to  perceive  the  general  laws  w^hich  would 
hold  in  any  case.  He  does  not  formally  demonstrate  these  laws, 
but  their  truth  can  be  inferred  from  what  he  has  previously  given, 
by  the  method  of  induction. 


24  G  EULEE. 

440.  As  an  example  of  Euler's  method  we  will  give  his  inves- 
tigation of  the  case  in  which  three  tickets  are  drawn. 

There  are  three  events  which  may  happen  which  may  be  repre- 
sented as  follows  : 

I.  a,  a-\-l,  a-\-2,  that  is  a  sequence  of  three. 

II.  a,  a  +  1;  h,  that  is  a  sequence  of  two,  the  number  h 
being  neither  a  +  2  nor  a  —  1. 

III.  a,  h,  c,  where  the  numbers  a,  Jj,  c  involve  no  sequence. 

I.  The  form  a,  a-\-l,  a +  2.  The  number  of  such  events  is 
n  —  2.  For  the  sequence  may  be  (1,  2,  3),  or  (2,  S,  4),  or  (3,  4,  5), 
up  to  (71  —2,n—l,  n). 

II.  The  form  a,  a  +  1,  h.  In  the  same  way  as  we  have  just 
shewn  that  the  number  of  sequences  of  three,  like  a,  a  +  1,  «  +  2, 
is  71  —  2,  it  follows  that  the  number  of  sequences  of  two,  like 
<2,  a  +  1,  is  7z  —  1.  Now  in  general  h  may  be  any  number  between 
1  and  n  inclusive,  except  a—1,  a,  a  +  1,  a  +  2;  that  is,  h  may  be 
any  number  out  of  ??  —  4  numbers.  But  in  the  case  of  the  first 
sequence  of  two,  namely  1,  2,  and  also  of  the  last  sequence  n  —  1,  71, 
the  number  of  admissible  values  of  J  is  n  —  3.  Hence  the  whole 
number  of  events  of  the  form  a,  «  +  1,  I,  is  (w  —  1)  (71  —  4)  +  2,  that 
is  71^  —  5n  +  Q),  that  is  {n  —  2)  {ii  —  3). 

III.  The  form  a,  h,  c.  Suppose  a  to  be  any  number,  then  h 
and  c  must  be  taken  out  of  the  numbers  from  1  to  a  —  2  inclusive, 
or  out  of  the  numbers  from  a  +  2  to  n  inclusive  ;  and  b  and  c  must 
not  be  consecutive.  Euler  investiofates  the  number  of  events 
which  can  arise.  It  will  however  be  sufficient  for  us  here  to  take 
another  method  which  he  has  also  given.  The  total  number  of 
events  is  the  number  of  combinations  of  7i  things  taken  3  at  a  time, 

that  is  — ^^ — —  .     The  number  of  events  of  the  third  kind 

can  be  obtained  by  subtracting  from  the  whole  number  the  num- 
ber of  those  of  the  first  and  second  kind  ;  it  is  therefore 

71  (n  —  1)  Cii  —  2)       ,       J,.  ,       ,,.       . 

17273 —  ~  ^''  ~  ^  ^"  ~  )  ~  ^'' "  ^- 


EULER.  94.7 

It  will  be  found  tliat  tliis  is 

(n  -  2)  (n  -  3)  {n  -  4) 
1.2^3  • 

The  chances  of  the  three  events  will  be  found  by  dividing 
the  number  of  ways  in  which  they  can  respectively  occur  by  the 
whole  number. 

Thus  we  obtain  for  I,  ii,  iii,  respectively 

2-3  2.3(^-3)  {n  -  3)  {n  -  4) 

71  (a -1)'       n{a-l)      '  n  (n  ~  1)       ' 

441.  Euler's  next  memoir  also  relates  to  a  lottery.  This 
memoir  is  entitled  Solution  d'lme  question  tres  difficile  dans  le 
Calcid  des  Prohahilites.  It  w^as  published  in  the  volume  for 
1769  of  the  Histoire  de  VAcad.  ...  Berlin;  the  date  of  publication 
is  1771  :  the  memoir  occupies  pages  285 — 302  of  the  volume. 

442.  The  first  sentences  give  a  notion  of  the  nature  of  the 
problem. 

C'est  le  plan  d'une  lotterie  qni  ni'a  fourni  cette  question,  que  je 
me  propose  de  developper.  Cette  lotterie  etoit  de  cinq  classes,  chacuue 
de  10000  billets,  parmi  lesquels  il  y  avoit  1000  prix  dans  chaque 
classe,  et  par  consequent  9000  bJancs.  Chaque  billet  devoit  passer 
par  toutes  les  cinq  classes;  et  cette  lotterie  avoit  cela  de  particulier 
qu'outre  les  prix  de  chaque  classe  on  s'engagooit  de  payer  un  ducat 
a  cliacun  de  ceux  dont  les  billets  auroient  passe  par  toutes  les  cinq  classes 
sans  rien  gagner. 

443.  We  may  put  it  perhaps  more  clearly  thus.  A  man 
takes  the  same  ticket  in  5  different  lotteries,  each  having  1000 
prizes  to  9000  blanks.  Besides  his  chance  of  the  prizes,  he  is  to 
have  £1  returned  to  him  if  he  gains  no  prize. 

The  question  which  Euler  discusses  is  to  determine  the  pro- 
bable sum  which  will  thus  have  to  be  paid  to  those  who  fail 
in  obtaining  jmzes. 

444.  Euler's  solution  is  very  ingenious.  Suppose  h  the  num- 
ber of  classes  in  the  lottery ;  let  n  be  the  number  of  prizes  in  each 
class,  and  m  the  number  of  blanks. 


24iS  EULER. 

Suppose  tlie  tickets  of  the  first  class  to  have  been  drawn,  and 
that  the  prizes  have  fallen  on  certain  n  tickets  A,  B,  G ... 

Let  the  tickets  of  the  second  class  be  now  drawn.  Required 
the  chance  that  the  prizes  will  fall  on  the  same  n  tickets  as 
before.     The  chance  is 

1.2 71 

(m  +  1)  (m+  2) {m  +  n)  ' 

And  in  like  manner  the  chance  that  the  prizes  in  all  the 
classes  will  fall  on  the  same  tickets  as  in  the  first  class,  is  obtained 
by  raising  the  fraction  just  given  to  the  power  k  —  1. 

Let  {(m  +  1)  (m  +  2) {m  +  n)Y~'=M, 

and  {1.2 nY''  =  a. 

Then  -^  is  the  chance  that  all  the  prizes  will  fall  on  the  same 

n  tickets.     In  this  case  there  are  m  persons  who  obtain  no  prize, 
and  so  the  managers  of  the  lottery  have  to  pay  m  ducats. 

445.  Now  consider  the  case  in  which  there  are  m  —  1  persons 
who  obtain  no  prize  at  all.  Here  besides  the  n  tickets  A,  B,  G,  ... 
which  gained  in  the  first  class,  one  of  the  other  tickets,  of  which 
the  number  is  m,  gains  in  some  one  or  more  of  the  remaining 
classes.  Denote  the  number  of  ways  in  which  this  can  happen  by 
^m.  Now  If  denotes  the  whole  number  of  cases  which  can 
happen  after  the  first  class  has  been  drawn.  Moreover  /3  is  in- 
dependent  of  m.  This  statement  involves  the  essence  of  Euler's 
solution.  The  reason  of  the  statement  is,  that  all  the  cases 
which  can  occur  will  be  produced  by  distributing  in  various 
ways  the  fresh  ticket  among  A,  B,  G,  ...  excluding  one  of  these 
to  make  way  for  it. 

In  like  manner,  in  the  case  in  which  there  are  m  —  2  persons 
who  obtain  no  prize  at  all,  there  are  two  tickets  out  of  the  m 
which  failed  at  first  that  gain  prizes  once  or  oftener  in  the  remain- 
ing classes.  The  number  of  ways  in  which  this  can  occur  may 
be  denoted  by  <ym  {in  —  1),  where  7  is  indejjendent  of  m. 

Proceeding  in  this  way  we  have  from  the  consideration  that 
the  sum  of  all  possible  cases  is  M 

M=  a  +  jSin  +  ym  (in  -  1)  +  3m  [m  —  1)  {in  -  2)  -f  . . .. 


EULER.  249 

Now  %  13,  'y,  ...  are  all  independent  of  m.  Hence  we  may  put 
in  succession  for  on  the  values  1,  2,  3,  ...  ;  and  we  shall  thus  be 
able  to  determine  /S,  y  — 

446.  Euler  enters  into  some  detail  as  to  the  values  of  /3,  7 . . . ; 
but  he  then  shews  that  it  is  not  necessary  to  find  their  values  for 
his  object. 

For  he  proposed  to  find  the  probable  expense  which  will  fall 
on  the  managers  of  the  lottery.  Now  on  the  first  hypothesis 
it  is  m  ducats,  on  the  second  it  is  m  —  1  ducats,  on  the  third  it 
is  m  —  2  ducats,  and  so  on.     Thus  the  probable  expense  is 

-r>  \am  +  /3m  (m  -  1)  +  jm  {m  -  1)  (m  —  2)  +  . . .  L 

=  -^  ja  +  /3(w-l)+7  (771-1)  (m-2)  +  ...L 

The  expression  in  brackets  is  what  we  shall  get  if  we  change 
m  into  m  —  1  in  the  right-hand  member  of  the  value  of  M  in 
Art.  445  ;  the  expression  therefore  is  what  M  becomes  when  Ave 
change  m  into  m  —  1.     Thus 

a  +  y5(m-l)  +7(7??-  1)  {m-2)  +  ... 

=  [m  (771  +  1)  . . .  (m  +  n  -  1)  }'"\ 

Thus  finally  the  probable  expense  is 


m    Y  ^ 


m 


/)n  +  Uj 


Euler  then  confirms  the  truth  of  this  simple  result  by  general 


reasoning. 


447.     We  have  next  to  notice  a  memoir  entitled  Eclaircisse- 
mens  sur  le  memoire  de  Mr.  De  La  Gra^ige)  inserS  dans  le    V'^ 

volume  de  Melanges  de  Turin,  concernant  la  methode  de  prendre  le 

milieu  entre  les  residtats  de  plusieurs  observations,  <^c.     Presente 

a  VAcademie  le  27  Nov.  1777.     This  memoir  was  published  in  the 

Nova  Acta  Acad.  ...  Petrop.  Tom.  3,  which  contains  the  history 

of  the   Academy   for   the   year    1785 ;   the   date   of  publication 

of  the  volume  is  1788  :  the  memoir  occupies  pages  289 — 297. 


250  EULEPu 

The  memoir  consists  of  explanations  of  psn't  of  that  memoir 
by  Lagrange  to  which  we  have  aUuded  in  Art.  371 ;  nothing  new 
is  given.  The  explanations  seem  to  have  been  written  for  the 
benefit  of  some  beginner  in  Algebra,  and  would  be  quite  un- 
necessary for  any  student  unless  he  were  very  indolent  or  very 
dull. 

4i8.  The  next  contribution  of  Euler  to  our  subject  relates  to 
a  lottery ;  the  problem  is  one  that  has  successively  attracted  the 
attention  of  De  Moivre,  Mallet,  Laplace,  Euler  and  Trembley. 
We  shall  find  it  convenient  before  we  give  an  account  of  Euler's 
solution  to  advert  to  what  had  been  previously  published  by 
De  Moivre  and  Laplace. 

In  De  Moivre's  Doctrine  of  Chances,  Problem  xxxix.  of  the 
third  edition  is  thus  enunciated:  To  find  the  Expectation  of  J., 
when  with  a  Die  of  any  given  number  of  Faces,  he  undertakes 
to  fling  any  numxber  of  them  in  any  given  number  of  Casts.  The 
problem,  as  we  have  already  stated,  first  appeared  in  the  De  Men- 
sura  Sortis.     See  Arts.  251  and  291. 

Let  71  be  the  number  of  faces  on  the  die ;  x  the  number  of 
throws,  and  suppose  that  m  specified  faces  are  to  come  up.  Then 
the  number  of  favourable  cases  is 

,f  _  ,„  u  -Vf-\-  ^^'^lH  (,,  _  2)-^  -  . . . 
^  ^  1.2^  ^ 

where  the  series  consists  of  m  +  1  terms.  The  whole  number  of 
possible  cases  is  if,  and  the  required  chance  is  obtained  by  di- 
viding the  number  of  favourable  cases  by  the  whole  number  of 
possible  cases. 

44^9.  The  following  is  De  Moivre's  method  of  investigation. 
First,  suppose  we  ask  in  how  many  ways  the  ace  can  come  up. 
The  whole  number  of  cases  is  7f ;  the  whole  number  of  cases 
if  the  ace  were  expunged  would  be  {n  —  iy  ;  thus  the  whole  number 
of  cases  in  which  the  ace  can  come  up  is  ;?/*"—  (n  —  ly. 

Next,  suppose  we  ask  in  how  many  ways  the  ace  and  deux 
can  come  up.  If  the  deux  were  expunged,  the  number  of  ways 
in  which  tlie  ace   could  come  up  would  l)e  [n  —  ly  —  {n  —  2y,  by 


EULER.  251 

what  we  have  just  seen  ;  this  therefore  is  the  niunber  of  ways 
in  which  with  the  given  die  the  ace  can  come  up  without  the  deux. 
Subtract  this  number  from  the  number  of  ways  in  which  the  ace 
can  come  up  with  or  without  the  deux,  and  we  have  left  the 
number  of  ways  in  which  the  ace  can  come  up  luith  the  deux. 
Thus  the  result  is 

n^-{n-ir-\{n-\r-{n-^.rr, 
that  is,  if  -2{n-  Vf  -f  {n  -  2f. 

De  Moivre  in  like  manner  briefly  considers  the  case  in  wdiich 
the  ace,  the  deux,  and  the  tray  are  to  come  up ;  he  then  states 
what  the  result  will  be  when  the  ace,  the  deux,  the  tray,  and 
the  quatre  are  to  come  up ;  and  finally,  he  enunciates  verbally 
the  general  result. 

De  Moivre  then  proceeds  to  shew  how  approximate  numerical 
values  may  be  obtained  from  the  formula ;  see  Art.  292. 

450.  The  result  may  be  conveniently  expressed  in  the  nota- 
tion of  Finite  Differences. 

The  number  of  ways  in  which  m  specified  faces  can  come  up 
is  A'"  (71  —  mY ;  where  m  is  of  course  not  greater  than  n. 

It  is  also  obvious  that  if  m  be  greater  than  x,  the  event 
required  is  impossible ;  and  in  fact  we  knoAv  that  the  expression 
A"'  (?z  —  my  vanishes  when  ?n  is  greater  than  x. 

Suppose  71  =  m  ;  then  the  number  of  ways  may  be  denoted  by 
A^O"^ ;  the  expression  written  at  full  is 

,f  _  ,,  (,,  _.  1)-  a.  ^^j-^-^  {^ri-Tf-... 

451.  One  particular  case  of  the  general  result  at  the  end 
of  the  preceding  Article  is  deserving  of  notice.  If  we  jDut  x  =  n, 
we  obtain  the  number  of  ways  in  which  all  the  71  faces  come  up 
in  n  throws.  The  sum  of  the  series  wdien  x  =  7i  is  known  to  be 
equal  to  the  product  1.2.3...??,  as  may  be  shewn  in  various 
ways.  But  we  may  remark  that  this  result  can  also  be  obtained 
by  the  Theory  of  Probability  itself;  for  if  all  the  7i  faces  are 
to  appear  in  ii  throws,  there  must  be  no  repetition  ;  and  thus  the 


'252  EULER. 

number  of  ways  is  the  number  of  permutations  of  n  things  taken 
all  together. 

Thus  we  see  that  the  sum  of  a  certain  series  might  be  inferred 
indirectly  by  the  aid  of  the  Theory  of  Probability ;  we  shall 
hereafter  have  a  similar  example. 

452.  In  the  Memoires ...  par  divers  Savans,  Vol.  VI.,  1775, 
page  363,  Laplace  solves  the  following  problem  :  A  lottery  con- 
sists of  n  tickets,  of  which  r  are  drawn  at  each  time ;  find  the 
probability  that  after  x  drawings,  all  the  numbers  will  have  been 
drawn. 

The  numbers  are  supposed  to  be  replaced  after  each  drawing. 

Laplace's  method  is  substantially  the  same  as  is  given  in  his 
Theorie . . .  des  Prob.,  page  192;  but  the  approximate  numerical 
calculations  which  occupy  pages  193 — 201  of  the  latter  work  do 
not  occur  in  the  memoir. 

Laplace  solves  the  problem  more  generally  than  he  enunciates 
it ;  for  he  finds  the  probability  that  after  x  drawings  m  specified 
tickets  will  all  have  been  drawn,  and  then  by  putting  n  for  m, 
the  result  for  the  particular  case  which  is  enunciated  is  obtained. 

453.  The  most  interesting  point  to  observe  is  that  the  pro- 
blem treated  by  Laplace  is  really  coincident  with  that  treated  by 
De  Moivre,  and  the  methods  of  the  two  mathematicians  are  sub- 
stantially the  same. 

In  De  Moivre's  problem  7i^  is  the  whole  number  of  cases ;  the 
corresponding  number  in  Laplace's  problem  is  [^  (n,  r)}'',  where 
by  (/)  (71,  r)  we  denote  the  number  of  combinations  of  n  things 
taken  r  at  a  time.  In  De  Moivre's  problem  (n  —  ly  is  the  whole 
number  of  cases  that  would  exist  if  one  face  of  the  die  were 
expunged ;  the  corresponding  number  in  Laplace's  problem  is 
j^(7i-l,  r)]^  Similarly  to  (n  —  2y  in  De  Moivre's  problem 
corresponds  [(f)  (n  —  2,  r)]"^  in  Laplace's.  And  so  on.  Hence,  in 
Laplace's  problem,  the  number  of  cases  in  which  m  specified 
tickets  will  be  drawn  is 

{<P  (n,  r)Y-m  {4,  («-  1,  r)}'  +  "^"~^^  (<^  (»-  2,  r)}' -  ...  ; 

and  the  probability  will  be  found  by  dividing  this  number  by  the 
whole  number  of  cases,  that  is  by  {</>  (?i,  r)}^ 


EULER.  253 

454.  With  the  notation  of  Finite  Differences  we  may  denote 
the  number  of  cases  favourable  to  the  drawing  of  m  specified 
tickets  by  A'"  {(/>  (n  — 7?^,  r)}^;  and  the  number  of  cases  favourable 
to  the  drawing  of  all  the  tickets  by  A"  {(/>  (0,  r)Y. 

455.  In  the  Histoire  de  VAcad.  ...  Paris,  1783,  Laplace  gives 
an  approximate  numerical  calculation,  which  also  occurs  in 
page  195  of  the  Theorie ...  des  Proh.  He  finds  that  in  a  lottery 
of  10000  tickets,  in  which  a  single  ticket  is  drawn  each  time,  it 
is  an  even  chance  that  all  will  have  been  drawn  in  about  957()7 
drawings. 

456.  After  this  notice  of  what  had  been  published  by  De 
Moivre  and  Laplace,  we  proceed  to  examine  Euler's  solution. 

The  problem  appears  in  Euler's  Opuscida  Analytica,  Vol.  Ii., 
1785.  In  this  volume  pages  331 — 346  are  occupied  with  a  memoir 
entitled  Solutio  quarundam  quaestionum  dijjiciliorum  in  calculo 
prohabilium.     Euler  begins  thus  : 

His  quaestionibus  occasionem  dedit  ludus  passim  publice  institutus, 
quo  ex  nonaginta  scliedulis,  numeris  1,  2,  3,  4,... 90  signatis,  statis  tem- 
poribus  quinae  schedulae  sorte  extrahi  sclent.  Hinc  ergo  hujusmodi 
quaestiones  oriuntur:  quanta  scilicet  sit  probabilitas  ut,  postquam  datus 
extractionum  numerus  fuerit  peractus,  vel  omnes  nonaginta  numeri 
exierint,  vel  saltern  89,  vel  88,  vel  pauciores.  Has  igitur  quaestiones, 
utpote  difficillimas,  hie  ex  principiis  calculi  Probabilium  jam  pridem  usu 
receptis,  resolvere  constitui.  Neque  me  deterrent  objectiones  Illustris 
lyAlembert,  qui  huuc  calculum  suspectum  reddere  est  conatiis.  Post- 
quam enim  summus  Geometra  studiis  mathematicis  valedixit,  lis  etiam 
helium  indixisse  videtur,  dum  pleraque  fundamenta  solidissinie  stabilita 
evertere  est  aggressus.  Quamvis  enim  hae  objectiones  apud  ignaros 
maximi  ponderis  esse  debeant,  hand  tamen  metuendum  est,  inde  ipsi 
scientiae  ullum  detrimentum  allatum  iri. 

457.  Euler  says  that  he  finds  a  certain  symbol  very  useful  in 
these  calculations ;  namely,  he  uses 

_q]  1.2 q 

458.  Euler  makes  no  reference  to  his  predecessors  De  Moivre 
and  Laplace.     He  gives  the  formula  for  the  chance  that  all  the 


254  EULEE. 

tickets  shall  be  drawn.     This  formula  corresponds  with  Laplace's. 
We  have  only  to  put  771  =  w  in  Art.  453. 

Euler  then  considers  the  question  in  which  n  —  1,  or  ?i  —  2, ... 
tickets  at  least  are  to  be  drawn.  He  discusses  successively  the 
first  case  and  the  second  case  briefly,  and  he  enunciates  his 
general  result.  This  is  tlie  following ;  suppose  we  require  that 
71  —  V  tickets  at  least  shall  be  drawn,  then  the  number  of  favour- 
able cases  is 

+  {i>  +  l)<j>  {»,  v+2){,j>{n-v-  2,  r)}' 

-  i^^H^-±^  ^  („,  ^  +  3){ct,in-v-  3,  r) }'-  . . . 

This  result  constitutes  the  addition  which  Euler  contributes  to 
what  had  been  known  before. 

459.  Euler's  method  requires  close  attention  in  order  to  gain 
confidence  in  its  accuracy ;  it  resembles  that  which  is  employed 
in  treatises  on  Algebra,  to  shew  how  many  integers  there  are 
which  are  less  than  a  given  number  and  prime  to  it.  We  will  give 
another  demonstration  of  the  result  which  will  be  found  easier 
to  follow. 

The  number  of  ways  in  which  exactly  m  tickets  are  drawn 
is  (^  (n,  m)  A'"  {</)  (0,  r)Y.  For  the  factor  A"^  [(\>  (0,  r)Y  is,  by 
Art.  454,  the  number  of  ways  in  which  in  a  lottery  of  m  tickets, 
all  the  tickets  will  appear  in  the  course  of  x  drawings ;  and 
0  (n,  77i)  is  the  number  of  combinations  of  ii  things  taken  m  at 
a  time. 

The  number  of  ways  in  which  n  —  v  tickets  at  least  will  appear, 
will  therefore  be  given  by  the  formula  S  </>  {ii,  m)  A"*  {^  (0,  r)Y, 
where  S  refers  to  m,  and  m  is  to  have  all  values  between  n  and 
n  —  v,  both  inclusive. 

Thus  we  get 

A"  [^  (0,  r)Y  +  «  A'-  [</>  (0,  r)r  +  ^^^-^  A»-[<^  (0,  ryf 
the  series  extending^  to  i^  +  1  terms. 


EULER.  255 

We  may  write  this  for  shortness  thus, 
{a-+  n  A--  +  4;^  A-  +  "  ^"^^;'-  ''  A-.  ...}  j^  (0,  ,.;}: 

Now  put  E—1  for  A,  expand,  and  reariange  in  powers  of  E; 
we  shall  thus  obtain 

1^"  -  (/>  {n,  V  +  1)  E''-'-'  -\-{v  +  l)^  {n,  V  +  2)  E"-'"' 

-  (^^±1)^^  ^  (.,  .  +  .3)  E-^  +  ...}  {^  (0,  .^  ; 

and  this  coincides  with  Euler's  result. 

We   shall  find  in  fact  that  when  we  put  E—1   for  A,  the 
coefficient  of  E''~^  is 

(-  '^y  \J1  U     n  ^P^P-^')    p{r-V){p-^-.^        I 

\p\n-p\       ^  "^       1.2  1.2.3  ■^•••j' 


where  the  series  in  brackets  is  continued  to  z^  + 1  terms,  unless 
p  be  less  than  z^  +  1  and  then  it  is  continued  to  jj  +  1  terms 
only.  In  the  former  case  the  sum  of  the  series  can  be  obtained  by 
taking  the  coefficient  of  x"  in  the  expansion  of  (1  —  xY  (1  -  xy\ 
that  is  in  the  expansion  of  (1  —  xY~^.  In  the  latter  case  the  sum 
would  be  the  coefficient  of  x^  in  the  same  expansion,  and  is  there- 
fore zero,  except  when  ^9  is  zero  and  then  it  is  unity. 

460.  Since  r  tickets  are  drawn  each  time,  the  greatest  number 
of  tickets  which  can  be  drawn  in  x  drawings  is  xr.  Thus,  as 
Euler  remarks,  the  expression 

[<^  («.  r)Y  -  n  [4>  [n  -  1,  r)Y  +  ^^^  {<i>  (u  -  2.  r)]' -  ... 

must  be  zero  if  n  be  greater  than  xr  ;  for  the  expression  gives  the 
number  of  ways  in  which  71  tickets  can  be  drawn  in  r  drawings. 
Euler  also  says  that  the  case  in  which  n  is  equal  to  xr  is  re- 
markable, for  then  the  expression  just  given  can  be  reduced  to 
a  product  of  factors,  namely  to 


256  EULER 

Euler  does  not  demonstrate  this  result;  perhaps  he  deduced 
it  from  the  Theory  of  ProbabiHty  itself.  For  if  xr  =  n,  it  is 
obvious  that  no  ticket  can  be  repeated,  when  all  the  tickets  are 
drawn  in  r  drawings.  Thus  the  whole  number  of  favourable  cases 
which  can  occur  at  the  first  drawing  must  be  the  number  of 
combinations  of  n  things  taken  r  at  a  time  ;  the  whole  number 
of  favourable  cases  which  can  occur  at  the  second  drawing  is  the 
number  of  combinations  of  ?2  —  r  things  taken  r  at  a  time  ;  and 
so  on.  Then  the  product  of  all  these  numbers  gives  the  whole 
number  of  favourable  cases. 

This  example  of  the  summation  of  a  series  indirectly  by  the  aid 
of  the  Theory  of  Probability  is  very  curious  ;  see  also  Art.  451. 

461.  Euler  gives  the  following  paragraph  after  stating  his 
formulae, 

In  his  probabilitatibiis  aestimandis  utique  assiimitur  omnes  litteras 
ad  extrahendum  aeque  esse  proclives,  quod  autem  111.  D^Alemhert  negat 
assumi  posse.  Arbitratur  enim,  simul  ad  omnes  tractus  jam  ante  per- 
actos  respici  oportere;  si  enim  quaepiam  litterae  nimis  crebro  fuerint 
extractae,  turn  eas  in  sequentibus  tractibus  rarius  exituras;  contrarium 
vero  eveniie  si  quaepiam  litterae  nimis  raro  exierint.  Haec  ratio,  si 
valeret,  etiam  valitura  esset  si  sequentes  tractus  demum  post  annum, 
vel  adeo  integrum  speculum,  quin  etiam  si  in  alio  quocunque  loco 
instituerentur ;  atque  ob  eandem  rationem  etiam  ratio  haberi  deberet 
omnium  tractuum,  qui  jam  olim  in  quibuscunque  terrae  locis  fuerint 
peracti,  quo  certe  vix  quicquam  absurdius  excogitari  potest. 

462.  In  Euler's  Opuscula  Analytica,  Yol.  ii.,  1785,  there  is 
a  memoir  connected  with  Life  Assurance.  The  title  is  Solutio 
quaestionis  ad  calculum  j)7vhahilitatis  pertinentis.  Quantum  duo 
conjuges  per^solvere  deheant,  ut  suis  haeredihus  post  utriusque 
mortem  certa  argenti  summa  persolvatiir.  The  memoir  occupies 
pages  315 — 330  of  the  volume. 

Euler  repeats  a  table  which  he  had  inserted  in  the  Berlin 
Memoirs  for  1760  ;  see  Art.  433.  The  table  shews  out  of  1000 
infants,  how  many  will  be  alive  at  the  end  of  any  given  year. 

Euler  supposes  that  in  order  to  ensure  a  certain  sum  when 
both  a  husband  and  wife  are  dead,  x  is  paid  down  and  z  paid 


EULEE.  257 

annually  besides,  until  both  are  dead.  He  investigates  the  re- 
lation which  must  then  hold  between  x,  z  and  the  sum  to  be 
ensured.  Thus  a  calculator  may  assign  an  arbitrary  value  to  two 
of  the  three  quantities  and  determine  the  third.  He  may  sup- 
pose, for  example,  that  the  sum  to  be  ensured  is  1000  Rubles, 
and  that  x  =  0,  and  find  z. 

Euler  does  not  himself  calculate  numerical  results,  but  he 
leaves  the  formulae  quite  ready  for  application,  so  that  tables 
might  be  easily  constructed. 


17 


CHAPTER    XIII. 


D'ALEMBERT. 


463.  D'Alembert  was  born  in  1717  and  died  in  1788.  This 
great  mathematician  is  known  in  the  history  of  the  Theory  of  Pro- 
bability for  his  opposition  to  the  opinions  generally  received ;  his 
high  reputation  in  science,  philosophy,  and  literature  have  secured 
an  amount  of  attention  for  his  paradoxes  and  errors  which  they 
would  not  have  gained  if  they  had  proceeded  from  a  less  distin- 
guished writer.  The  earliest  publication  of  his  peculiar  opinions 
seems  to  be  in  the  article   Croix  ou  Pile  of  the  Fncyclopedie  ou 

Dictionnaire  Raisonne We  will  speak  of  this  work  simply  as 

the  Encyclopedie,  and  thus  distinguish  it  from  its  successor  the 
Encyclopedie  M^thodique.  The  latter  work  is  based  on  the  former ; 
the  article  Croiw  ou  Pile  is  reproduced  unchanged  in  the  latter. 

464.  The  date  of  the  volume  of  the  Encyclopedie  containing 
the  article  Croix  ou  Pile,  is  1754.  The  question  proposed  in  the 
article  is  to  find  the  chance  of  throwing  head  in  the  course  of  two 
throws  with  a  coin.  Let  H  stand  for  head,  and  T  for  taiL  Then 
the  common  theory  asserts  that  there  are  four  cases  equally  likely, 
namely,   HH,    TH,   II2\    TT\  the   only  unfavourable  case  is  the 

3 

last ;   therefore  the  required  chance  is  - .      D'Alembert  however 

4 

doubts  whether  this  can  be  correct.     He  says  that  if  head  appears 

at  the  first  throw  the  game  is  finished  and  therefore  there  is  no 


d'alembert.  259 

need  of  the   second  throw.     Thus   he   makes    only  three   cases, 

2 
namely,  H,  TH,  TT\  therefore  the  chance  is  ^. 

o 

Similarly  in  the  case  of  three  throws  he  makes  only  four  cases, 
namely,  H,  TH,  TTE,  TTT:  therefore  the  chance  is  |.  The 
common  theory  would  make  eight  equally  likely  cases,  and  obtain 
-  for  the  chance. 

465.  In  the  same  article  D'Alembert  notices  the  Petersburg 
Problem.     He  refers  to  the  attempts  at  a  solution  in  the   Com- 

mentarii   Acad Petrop.   Vol.    v,    which   w^e    have    noticed    in 

Arts.  889 — 393  ;  he  adds :  mais  nous  ne  savons  si  on  en  sera  satis- 
fait ;  et  il  y  a  ici  quelque  scandale  qui  merite  bien  d'occuper  les 
Algebristes.  D'Alembert  says  we  have  only  to  see  if  the  expecta- 
tion of  one  player  and  the  corresponding  risk  of  the  other  really 
is  infinite,  that  is  to  say  greater  than  any  assignable  finite  number. 
He  says  that  a  little  reflexion  will  shew  that  it  is,  for  the  risk 
augments  wdth  the  number  of  throws,  and  this  number  may  by  the 
conditions  of  the  game  proceed  to  any  extent.  He  concludes  that 
the  fact  that  the  game  may  continue  for  ever  is  one  of  the  reasons 
wdiich  produce  an  infinite  expectation. 

D'Alembert  proceeds  to  make  some  further  remarks  w^hich  are 
repeated  in  the  second  volume  of  his  Ojniscides,  and  which  will 
come  under  our  notice  hereafter.  We  shall  also  see  that  in  the 
fourth  volume  of  his  Opuscules  D'Alembert  in  fact  contradicts  the 
conclusion  which  w^e  have  just  noticed. 

466.  We  have  next  to  notice  the  article  Gageure,  of  the 
Encyclopedie;  the  volume  is  dated  1757.  D'Alembert  says  he  wall 
take  this  occasion  to  insert  some  ver}^  good  objections  to  what  he 
had  given  in  the  article  Croix  ou  Pile.  He  says,  Elles  sont  de 
M.  Necker  le  fils,  citoyen  de  Geneve,  professeur  de  Mathematiques 
en  cette  ville,  ...  nous  les  avons  extraits  d'une  de  ses  lettres.  The 
objections  are  three  in  number.  First  Necker  denies  that  D'Alem- 
bert's  three  cases  are  equally  likely,  and  justifies  this  denial. 
Secondly  Necker  gives  a  good  statement  of  the  solution  on  the 

17—2 


2(j0  d'alembert. 

ordinary  theory.  Thirdly,  he  shews  that  D'Alembert's  view  is 
inadmissible  as  leading  to  a  result  which  is  obviously  untrue  :  this 
objection  is  given  by  D'Alembert  in  the  second  volume  of  his 
Opuscules,  and  will  come  before  us  hereafter.  D'Alembert  after 
giving  the  objections  says,  Ces  objections,  sur-tout  la  derniere, 
meritent  sans  doute  beaucoup  d'attention.  But  still  he  does  not 
admit  that  he  is  convinced  of  the  soundness  of  the  common  theory. 

The  article  Gageure  is  not  reproduced  in  the  Encyclopklie 
M<itliodique. 

467.  D'Alembert  wrote  various  other  articles  on  our  subject 
in  the  E ncy dope  die ;  but  they  are  unimportant.  We  will  briefly 
notice  them. 

Als3nt.  In  this  article  D'Alembert  alludes  to  the  essay  by 
Nicolas  Bernoulli ;  see  Art.  338. 

Avantage.     This  article  contains  nothing  remarkable. 

Bassette.  This  article  contains  a  calculation  of  the  advantage 
of  the  Banker  in  one  case,  namely  that  given  by  Montmort  on  his 
page  145. 

Carreau.  This  article  gives  an  account  of  the  sorts  de  jeu  dont 
M.  de  Buff  on  a  donne  le  calcid  in  1733,  avant  que  d'etre  de 
V Academie  des  Sciences ;  see  Art.  354. 

De.  This  article  shews  all  the  throws  which  can  be  made  with 
two  dice,  and  also  with  three  dice. 

Loterie.  This  is  a  simple  article  containing  ordinary  remarks 
and  examples. 

Pari.  This  article  consists  of  a  few  lines  giving  the  ordinary 
rules.  At  the  end  we  read  :  Au  reste,  ces  regies  doivent  ^tre  modi- 
fiees  dans  certains  cas,  ou  la  probabilite  de  gagner  est  fort  petite, 
et  celle  de  perdre  fort  grande.  Voyez  Jeu.  There  is  however 
nothing  in  the  article  Jeu  to  which  this  remark  can  apply,  which 
is  the  more  curious  because  of  course  Jeu  precedes  Pari  in  alpha- 
betical order;  the  absurdity  is  reproduced  in  the  Encyclopedic 
M4thodi€[ue. 

The  article  Prohahilite  in  the  Encyclopedie  is  apparently  by 
Diderot.  It  gives  the  ordinary  view  of  the  subject  with  the  excep- 
tion of  the  point  which  we  have  noticed  in  Art.  91. 


d'alembert.  261 

468.  In  various  places  in  his  Ojyuscules  Mathematiques  D'Alem- 
bert  gives  remarks  on  the  Theory  of  ProbabiUties.  These  remarks 
are  mainly  directed  against  the  first  principles  of  the  subject  which 
D'Alembert  professes  to  regard  as  unsound.  We  will  now  examine 
all  the  places  in  which  these  remarks  occur. 

469.  In  the  second  volume  of  the  Opuscules  the  first  memoir 
is  entitled  Reflexions  silt  le  calcul  des  Prohabilites ;  it  occupies 
pages  1 — 25.  The  date  of  the  volume  is  1761.  D'Alembert 
begins  by  quoting  the  common  rule  for  expectation  in  the  Theory 
of  Probability,  namely  that  it  is  found  by  taking  the  product  of  the 
loss  or  gain  which  an  event  will  produce,  by  the  probability  that 
this  event  will  happen.  D'Alembert  says  that  this  rule  had  been 
adopted  by  all  analysts,  but  that  cases  exist  in  which  the  rule 
seems  to  fail. 

470.  The  first  case  wdiich  D'Alembert  brings  forward  is  that 
of  the  Petersburg  Problem;  see  Art.  389.  By  the  ordinary  theory 
A  ought  to  give  B  an  infinite  sum  for  the  privilege  of  playing 
with  him.     D'Alembert  says. 

Or,  independamment  de  ce  qu'une  somme  infinie  est  line  cliimere, 
11  n'y  a  personne  qui  vouliit  douner  pour  jouer  a  ce  jeu,  je  ne  dis  pas 
une  somme  infinie,  mais  meme  une  somme  assez  modique. 

471.  D'Alembert  notices  a  solution  of  the  Petersburg  Problem 
which  had  been  communicated  to  him  by  un  Geometre  celebre 
de  I'Academie  des  Sciences,  plein  de  savoir  et  de  sagacite.  He 
means  Fontaine  I  presume,  as  the  solution  is  that  which  Fontaine 
is  known  to  have  given ;  see  Montucla,  page  403  :  in  this  solution 
the  fact  is  considered  that  B  cannot  pay  more  than  a  certain  sum, 
and  this  limits  what  A  ought  to  give  to  induce  B  to  play.  D'Alem- 
bert says  that  this  is  unsatisfactory ;  for  suppose  it  is  agreed  that 
the  game  shall  only  extend  to  a  finite  number  of  trials,  say  100  ; 
then  the  theory  indicates  that  A  should  give  50  crowns.  D'Alem- 
bert asserts  that  this  is  too  much. 

The  answer  to  D'Alembert  is  simple ;  and  it  is  very  well  put  in 
fact  by  Condorcet,  as  we  shall  see  hereafter.  The  ordinary  rule  is 
entitled  to  be  adopted,  because  in  the  long  run  it  is  equally  fair  to 


262  d'alembeet. 

both  parties  A  and  B,  and  any  other  rule  would  be  unfah^  to  one 
or  the  other. 

472.  D'Alembert  concludes  from  his  remarks  that  when  the 
probability  of  an  event  is  very  small  it  ought  to  be  regarded  and 
treated  as  zero.  For  example  he  says,  suppose  Peter  plays  with 
James  on  this  condition  ;  a  coin  is  to  be  tossed  one  hundred  times, 
and  if  head  appear  at  the  last  trial  and  not  before,  James  shall  give 
2^^^  crowns  to  Peter.  By  the  ordinary  theory  Peter  ought  to  give 
to  James  one  crown  at  the  beginning  of  the  game. 

D'Alembert  says  that  Peter  ought  not  to  give  this  crown 
because  he  will  certainly  lose,  for  head  will  appear  before  the 
hundredth  trial,  certainly  though  not  necessarily. 

D'Alembert's  doctrine  about  a  small  probability  being  equi- 
valent to  zero  was  also  maintained  by  Buffon. 

473.  D'Alembert  says  that  we  must  distinguish  between  what 
is  metaphysically  possible,  and  what  is  physically  possible.  In  the 
first  class  are  included  all  those  things  of  which  the  existence  is  not 
absurd  ;  in  the  second  class  are  included  only  those  things  of  which 
the  existence  is  not  too  extraordinary  to  occur  in  the  ordinary 
course  of  events.  It  is  metaphysically  possible  to  throw  two  sixes 
with  two  dice  a  hundred  times  running  ;  but  it  is  physically  impos- 
sible, because  it  never  has  happened  and  never  will  happen. 

This  is  of  course  only  saying  in  another  way  that  a  very  small 
chance  is  to  be  regarded  and  treated  as  zero.  DAlembert  shews 
however,  that  when  we  come  to  ask  at  what  stage  in  the  diminu- 
tion of  chance  we  shall  consider  the  chance  as  zero,  we  are  in- 
volved in  difficulty ;  and  he  uses  this  as  an  additional  argument 
against  the  common  theory. 

See  also  Mill's  Logic,  1862,  Vol.  ii.  page  170. 

474.  D'Alembert  says  he  will  propose  an  idea  which  has 
occurred  to  him,  by  which  the  ratio  of  probabilities  may  be 
estimated.  The  idea  is  simply  to  make  experiments.  He  ex- 
emplifies it  by  supposing  a  coin  to  be  tossed  a  large  number  of 
times,  and  the  results  to  be  observed.  We  shall  find  that  this 
has  been  done  at  the  instance  of  Buffon  and  others.  It  is  need- 
less to  say  that  the  advocates  of  the  common  Theory  of  Proba- 


d'alembeht.  263 

bility  would  be  quite  willing  to  accept  D'Alembert's  reference  to 
experiment ;  for  relying  on  the  theorem  of  James  Bernoulli,  they 
would  have  no  doubt  that  experiment  would  confirm  their  calcula- 
tions. It  is  however  curious  that  D'Alembert  proceeds  in  his 
very  next  paragraph  to  make  a  remark  which  is  quite  inconsistent 
with  his  appeal  to  experiment.  For  he  says  that  if  head  has 
arrived  three  times  in  succession,  it  is  more  likely  that  the  next 
arrival  will  be  tail  than  head.  He  says  that  the  oftener  head 
has  arrived  in  succession  the  more  likely  it  is  that  tail  will 
arrive  at  the  next  throw.  He  considers  that  this  is  obvious,  and 
that  it  furnishes  another  example  of  the  defects  of  the  ordinary 
theory.  In  the  Opuscules,  Vol.  iv.  pages  90 — 92,  D'Alembert 
notices  the  charge  of  inconsistency  which  may  be  urged  against 
him,  and  attempts  to  reply  to  it. 

475.  D'Alembert  then  proceeds  to  another  example,  which, 
as  he  intimates,  he  had  already  given  in  the  Encyclopedie,  under 
the  titles  Croix  ou  Pile  and  Gageure ;  see  Art.  463.  The  question 
is  this  :  required  the  probability  of  throwing  a  head  with  a  coin 
in  two  trials. 

D'Alembert  came  to  the  conclusion  in  the  Encyclopedie  that 

2  3 

the  chance  ought  to  be  ^  instead  of  -r .     In  the  Opuscides  how- 

ever  he  does   not  insist  very  strongly  on  the  correctness  of  the 

2 
result  ^  ,  but  seems  to  be  content  with  saying  that  the  reasoning 
o 

3 

which  jDroduces  j  is  unsound. 

D'Alembert  urges  his  objections  against  the  ordinary  theory 
with  great  pertinacity ;  and  any  person  who  wishes  to  see  all  that 
a  gi'eat  mathematician  could  produce  on  the  wrong  side  of  a 
question  should  consult  the  original  memoir.  But  we  agree  with 
every  other  ^^Titer  on  the  subject  in  thinking  that  there  is  no 
real  force  in  D'Alembert's  objections. 

476.  The  folloAving  extract   will  shew  that   D'Alembert  no 

2 
longer  insisted  on  the  absolute  accuracy  of  the  result  ^  : 


264^  d'alembekt. 

Je  ne  voudrois  pas  cependant  regarder  en  toute  rigueur  les  trois  coups 
dont  il  s'agit,  comme  egalement  possibles.  Car  1°,  il  povirroit  se  faire 
en  effet  (et  je  suis  meme  porte  a  le  croire),  que  le  cas  pile  croix  ne  fut 
pas  exactement  aussi  possible  que  le  cas  croix  seiil;  mais  le  rapport  des 
possibilites  me  paroit  inappretiable.  2".  II  poiirroit  se  faire  encore  que 
le  coup  2)il&  croix  fiit  un  peu  plus  possible  que  pile  pile,  par  cette  seule 
raison  que  dans  le  dernier  le  meme  effet  arrive  deux  fois  de  suite;  mais 
le  rapport  des  possibilites  (suppose  qu'elles  soient  inegales),  n'est  pas 
plus  facile  a  etablir  dans  ce  second  cas,  que  dans  le  premier.  Ainsi 
il  pourroit  tres-bien  se  faire  que  dans  le  cas  propose,  le  rapport  des 
probabilites  ne  fut  ni  de  3  a  1,  ni  de  2  a  1  (comme  nous  I'avons  sup- 
pose dans  VUncyclopeclie)  mais  un  incommensurable  ou  inappretiable, 
moyen  entre  ces  deux  nombres.  Je  crois  cependant  que  cet  incommen- 
surable approcliera  plus  de  2  que  de  3,  parce  qu' encore  une  fois  il  n'y 
a  que  trois  cas  possibles,  et  non  pas  quatre.  Je  crois  de  meme  et  par 
les  memes  raisons,  que  dans  le  cas  ou  Ton  joueroit  en  trois  coups,  le 
rapport  de  3  a  1,  que  donne  ma  methode,  est  plus  pres  du  vrai,  que 
le  rapport  de  7  h  1,  donne  par  la  methode  ordinaire,  et  qui  me  paroit 
exorbitant. 

477.  D'Alembert  returns  to  the  objection  which  had  been 
urged  against  his  method,  and  which  he  noticed  under  the  title 
Gageure  in  the  EncyclopMie ;  see  Art.  466.  Let  there  be  a 
die  with  three  faces,  A,  B,  C ;  then  according  to  DAlembert's 
original  method  in  the  Encydopedie,  the  chances  would  always 
be  rather  against  the  appearance  of  a  specified  face  A,  however 
great  the  number  of  trials.  Suppose  n  trials,  then  by  DAlembert's 
method  the  chance  for  the  appearance  of  A  is  to  the  chance 
against  it  as  2"  —  1  is  to  2". 

For  example,  suppose  ti  =  8  :  then  the  favourable  cases  are 
A,  BA,  CA,  BBA,  BOA,  CCA,  CBA  ;  the  unfavourable  cases  are 
BBB,  BBC,  BOB,  BCG,  CBB,  GBG,  GGG,  GGB:  thus  the  ratio 
is  that  of  7  to  8.  D'Alembert  now  admits  that  these  cases  are 
not  equally  likely  to  happen  ;  though  he  believes  it  difficult  to 
assign  their  ratio  to  one  another. 

Thus  we  may  say  that  D'Alembert  started  with  decided  but 
erroneous  opinions,  and  afterwards  passed  into  a  stage  of  general 
doubt  and  uncertainty;  and  the  dubious  honour  of  effecting  the 
transformation  may  be  attributed  to  Necker. 


d'alembert.  265 

478.  D'Alembert  thus  sums  up  his  results,  on  his  page  24  : 

Concluons  de  toutes  ces  reflexions  j  1".  que  si  la  regie  que  j'ai  donnee 
dans  Y Encyclopedie  (faute  d'en  connoitre  une  meilleure)  pour  deter- 
miner le  rapport  des  probabilites  au  jeu  de  croix  et  pile,  n'est  point 
exacte  a  la  rigueur,  la  regie  ordinaire  pour  determiner  ce  rapport,  Test 
encore  moins;  2".  que  pour  parvenh  a  une  tlieorie  satisfaisante  du  cal- 
cul  des  probabilites,  il  faudroit  resoudre  plusieurs  Problemes  qui  sont 
peut-etre  insolubles;  savoir,  d'assigner  le  vrai  rapport  des  probabilites 
dans  les  cas  qui  ne  sont  pas  egalement  possibles,  ou  qui  peuvent 
n'etre  pas  regardes  conime  tels;  de  determiner  quand  la  j)robabilite 
doit  etre  regardee  comme  nulle ;  de  fixer  enfin  comment  on  doit  estimer 
I'esperance  ou  I'enjeu,  selon  que  la  probabilite  est  2)lus  ou  moins  grande. 

479.  The  next  memoir  by  D'Alembert  which  we  have  to 
notice  is  entitled  Sur^  Vwpplication  du  Calcid  des  Prohahilites  a 
Vinocidation  de  la  petite  Verole ;  it  is  published  in  the  second 
volume  of  the  Opuscules.  The  memoir  and  the  accompanying 
notes  occupy  pages  26 — 95  of  the  volume. 

480.  "We  have  seen  that  Daniel  Bernoulli  had  written  a 
memoir  in  which  he  had  declared  himself  very  strongly  in  favour 
of  Inoculation  ;  see  Art.  398.  The  present  memoir  is  to  a  certain 
extent  a  criticism  on  that  of  Daniel  Bernoulli.  D'Alembert  does 
not  deny  the  advantages  of  Inoculation  ;  on  the  contrary,  he  is 
rather  in  favour  of  it :  but  he  thinks  that  the  advantages  and 
disadvantages  had  not  been  properly  compared  by  Daniel  Ber- 
noulli, and  that  in  consequence  the  former  had  been  overestimated. 
The  subject  is  happily  no  longer  of  the  practical  importance  it 
was  a  century  ago,  so  that  we  need  not  give  a  very  full  account 
of  D'Alembert's  memoir ;  we  shall  be  content  with  stating  some 
of  its  chief  points. 

481.  Daniel  Bernoulli  had  considered  the  subject  as  it  related 
to  the  state,  and  had  shewn  that  Inoculation  was  to  be  recom- 
mended, because  it  augmented  the  mean  duration  of  life  for 
the  citizens.  D'Alembert  considers  the  subject  as  it  relates  to 
a  private  individual :  suppose  a  person  who  has  not  yet  been 
attacked  by  small-pox ;  the  question  for  him  is,  whether  he  will 
be  inoculated,  and  thus  run  the  risk,  small  though  it  may  be, 
of  dying  in  the  course  of  a  few  days,  or  whether  he  will  take  his 


2GG  d'aleivibert. 

cliauc3  of  escaping  entirely  from  an  attack  of  small-pox  during 
his  life,  or  at  least  of  recovering  if  attacked. 

D'Alembert  thinks  that  the  prosj^ect  held  out  to  an  individual 
of  a  gain  of  three  or  four  years  in  the  probable  duration  of  his 
hfe,  may  perhaps  not  be  considered  by  him  to  balance  the  im- 
mediate danger  of  submitting  to  Inoculation.  The  relative  value 
of  the  alternatives  at  least  may  be  too  indefinite  to  be  estimated ; 
so  that  a  person  may  hesitate,  even  if  he  does  not  altogether 
reject  Inoculation. 

482.  D'Alembert  lays  great  stress  on  the  consideration  that 
the  additional  years  of  life  to  be  gained  form  a  remote  and  not 
a  present  benefit ;  and  moreover,  on  account  of  the  infirmities  of 
age,  the  later  years  of  a  life  must  be  considered  of  far  less  value 
than  the  years  of  early  manhood. 

D'Alembert  distinguishes  between  the  physical  life  and  the 
real  life  of  an  individual.  By  the  former,  he  means  life  in  the 
ordinary  sense,  estimated  by  total  duration  in  years ;  by  the  latter, 
he  means  that  portion  of  existence  during  which  the  individual  is 
free  from  suffering,  so  that  he  may  be  said  to  enjoy  life. 

Again,  with  respect  to  utility  to  his  country,  D'Alembert  dis- 
tinguishes between  the  p)liysical  life  and  the  civil  life.  During 
infancy  and  old  age  an  individual  is  of  no  use  to  the  state ;  he 
is  a  burden  to  it,  for  he  must  be  supported  and  attended  by 
others.  During  this  period  D'Alembert  considers  that  the  indi- 
vidual is  a  charge  to  the  state ;  his  value  is  negative,  and  becomes 
positive  for  the  intermediate  periods  of  his  existence.  The  civil 
life  then  is  measured  by  the  excess  of  the  productive  period  of 
existence  over  that  which  is  burdensome. 

Relying  on  considerations  such  as  these,  D'Alembert  does  not 
admit  the  great  advantage  which  the  advocates  for  Inoculation  found 
in  the  fact  of  the  prolongation  of  the  mean  duration  of  human 
life  effected  by  the  operation.  He  looks  on  the  problem  as  far 
more  difficult  than  those  who  had  discussed  it  appeared  to  have 
supposed. 

483.  We  have  seen  that  Daniel  Bernoulli  assumed  that  the 
small-pox  attacked  every   year    1   in  ii   of  those  not  previously 


d'alembeht.  2G7 

attacked,  and  that  1  died  out  of  every  m  attacked  ;  on  these 
hypotheses  he  solved  definitely  the  problem  which  he  undertook. 
D'Alembert  also  gives  a  mathematical  theory  of  inoculation ;  but  he 
does  not  admit  that  Daniel  Bernoulli's  assumptions  are  established 
by  observations,  and  as  he  does  not  replace  them  by  others,  he 
cannot  bring  out  definite  results  like  Daniel  Bernoulli  does. 
There  is  nothing  of  special  interest  in  D'Alembert's  mathematical 
investigation;  it  is  rendered  tedious  by  several  figures  of  curves 
which  add  nothing  to  the  clearness  of  the  process  they  are  sup- 
posed to  illustrate. 

The  follomng  is  a  specimen  of  the  investigations,  rejecting  the 
encumbrance  of  a  figure  which  D'Alembert  gives. 

Suppose  a  large  number  of  infants  born  nearly  at  the  same 
epoch ;  let  y  represent  the  number  alive  at  the  end  of  a  certain 
time ;  let  ti  represent  the  number  who  have  died  during  this 
period  of  small-pox :  let  z  represent  the  number  who  would  have 
been  alive  if  small-pox  did  not  exist :  required  z  in  terms  of  y 
and  u. 

Let  dz  denote  the  decrement  of  ^  in  a  small  time,  dy  the 
decrement  of  y  in  the  same  time.  If  we  supposed  the  z  individuals 
subject  to  small-pox,  we  should  have 

dz  =  -  dii. 

y  ^ 

But  we  must  subtract  from  this  value  of  dz  the  decrement 

arising  from  small-pox,  to  which  the  z  individuals  are  by  hypo- 

z 
thesis  not  liable  :  this  is  -  du. 

y 

Thus,  dz  =  -  dy  +  -  du  ; 

y        y 

z                              z 
we  put  -^  -  du  and  not du,  because  z  and  y  diminish  while 

/       y  y 

u  increases.     Then 

dz     dif     du 

^     y     y 


therefore  log  z  =  \ogy  +  \  — 

/du 


268  d'alembert. 

The  result  is  not  of  practical  use  because  the  value  of  the 

C  Ciu 
integral  1—  is   not   known.     D'Alembert  gives  several  formulie 

which  involve  this  or  similar  unfinished  integrations. 

484.  D'Alembert  draws  attention  on  his  page  74  to  the  two 

distinct  methods  by  which  we  may  propose  to  estimate  the  espe- 

7'ance  de  vivre  for  a  person  of  given  age.    The  mean  duration  of 

life  is  the  average  duration   in  the  ordinary  sense   of  the  word 

average ;  the  j^^^^ohahle  duration  is  such  a  duration  that  it  is  an 

even  chance  whether  the  individual  exceeds  it  or  falls  short  of  it. 

Thus,  according  to  Halley's  tables,  for  an  infant  the  7nea)i  life  is 

26  years,  that  is  to  say  if  we  take  a  large  number  N  of  infants 

the  sum    of  the  years  of  their  lives  will  be  2QN;  the  probable 

N 
life  is  8  years,  that  is  to  say  ^  of  the   infants  die  under  8  years 

N 
old  and   -  die  over  8  years  old. 

Li 

The  terms  mea/i  life  and  probable  life  which  we  here  use  have 
not  always  been  appropriated  in  the  sense  we  here  explain ;  on  the 
contrary,  what  we  call  the  mean  life  has  sometimes  been  called 
the  probable  life.  D'Alembert  does  not  propose  to  distinguish  the 
two  notions  by  such  names  as  we  have  used.  His  idea  is  rather 
that  each  of  them  might  fairly  be  called  the  duration  of  life  to  be 
expected,  and  that  it  is  an  objection  against  the  Theory  of  Proba- 
bility that  it  should  apparently  give  two  different  results  for  the 
same  problem. 

485.  We  will  illustrate  the  point  as  D'Alembert  does,  by  means 
of  what  he  calls  the  curve  of  mortaliti/. 

Let  X  denote  the  number  of  years  measured  from  an  epoch ;  let 
yjr  (x)  denote  the  number  of  persons  alive  at  the  end  of  x  years 
from  birth,  out  of  a  large  number  born  at  the  same  time.  Let 
'yjr  (x)  be  the  ordinate  of  a  curve  ;  then  yjr  (x)  diminishes  from 
X  =  0  to  X  =  c,  say,  where  c  is  the  greatest  age  that  persons  can 
attain,  namely  about  100  years. 

This  curve  is  called  the  curve  of  mortality  by  D'Alembert. 


d'alembert.  2G9 

The  mean  duration  of  life  for  persons  of  the  age  a  years  is 

I   -v/r  (x)  dx 


a 


The  probable  duration  is  a  quantity  h  such  that 

This  is  D'Alembert's  mode.  We  might  however  use  another 
curve  or  function.  Let  cf)  (x)  be  such  that  <^  (x)  dx  represents  the 
number  who  die  in  an  element  of  time  dx.  Then  the  mean  dura- 
tion of  life  for  j)ersons  aged  a  years  is 

I    (a?  —  a)  (f)  (x)  dx 


a 


I   </)  (x)  dx 

J  a 

The  probable  duration  is  a  quantity  h  such  that 

I   (f)  (x)  dx  =  I   cj)  (x)  dx, 


that  is  I   (f>  (x)  dx  =  -  j   (f)  (x)  dx. 

Thus  the  mean  duration  is  represented  by  the  abscissa  of  the 
centre  of  gi'avity  of  a  certain  area ;  and  the  probable  duration  is 
represented  by  the  abscissa  corresponding  to  the  ordinate  which 
bisects  that  area. 

This  is  the  modern  method  of  illustrating  the  point ;  see 
Art.  101  of  the  Theory  of  Probability  in  the  Encyclopcedia  Metro- 
politana. 

486.  We  may  easily  shew  that  the  two  methods  of  the  pre- 
ceding Article  agree. 

For  we  have  <f)(x)  ——  h  -^fr'  (x),  where  Jc  is  some  constant. 
Therefore 

I  {x  —  a)<f>  (x)  dx      j  (x  —  ^)  ^'  (^)  <^'^ 

. '  a J_a . 

I  <^  (x)  dx  I  -v/r'  (x)  dx 

J  a  -'a 


270  d'alemfsErt. 

iind  I  (x  —  «)  -v/r'  (x)  dx  =  (x  —  a)  ^jr  {x)  —  I  yfr  (x)  dx, 
therefore  I  (x  —  a)  yjr'  (x)  dx  =  —  j  yjr  (x)  dx; 

and  \//'  (x)  dx=:  —  yjr  (a). 


a 


Thus 


I  (a?  —  a)  (p  (x)  dx       I  yjr  (x)  dx 

a  .'  a 


V  (.X)  dx  ^  ^"^ 


a 


This  shews  that  ihe  two  methods  give  the  same  mean  duration. 
In  the  same  way  it  may  be  shewn  that  they  give  the  same  pyvhahle 
duration. 

487.  D'Alembert  draws  attention  to  an  erroneous  solution  of 
the  problem  respecting  the  advantages  of  Inoculation,  which  he 
says  was  communicated  to  him  by  un  savant  Geotnetre.  D'Alem- 
bert  shews  that  the  solution  must  be  erroneous  because  it  leads  to 
untenable  results  in  two  cases  to  which  he  applies  it.  But  he  does 
not  shew  the  nature  of  the  error,  or  explain  the  principle  on  which 
the  pretended  solution  rests ;  and  as  it  is  rather  curious  we  will 
now  consider  it. 

Suppose  that  N  infants  are  born  at  the  same 
epoch,  and  let  a  table  of  mortality  be  formed  by 
recording  how  many  die  in  each  year  of  all  dis- 
eases excluding  small-pox,  and  also  how  many  die 

of  small-pox.    Let  the  table  be  denoted  as  here  ;       

so  that  u^  denotes  the  number  who  die  in  the  r*'^  year  excluding 
those  who  die  of  small-pox,  and  v,.  denotes  the  number  who  die  of 
small-pox.  Then  we  can  use  the  table  in  the  following  way  :  sup- 
pose M  any  other  number,  then  if  u^  die  in  the  r*''  year  out  of  N 

M 
from  all  diseases  except  small-pox,  -^^  w,.  would  die  out  of  M;  and 

so  for  any  other  proportion. 

Now  suppose  small-pox  eradicated  from  the  list  of  human  dis- 
eases ;  required  to  construct  a  new  table  of  mortality  from  the 
above  data.     The  savant  Geometre  proceeds  thus.     He  takes  the 


1 

^1 

^'l 

2 

^'■2 

^'2 

3 

«'3 

% 

4 

^^4 

^'4 

d'alembert.  271 

preceding  table  and  destroys  the  colmnn  v^,  v^,  ^3>  •••  Then  he 
assumes  that  the  remaining  column  will  shew  the  correct  mortality 
for  the  number  N—n  at  starting,  where  n  is  the  total  number  who 
died  of  small-pox,  that  is  n  —  v^-\- v^-\-v^+  ... 

M 

Thus  if  we  start  w4th  the  number  M  of  infants  ^r^ ?<,.  would 

N-n    ' 

die  on  this  assumption  in  the  r^^  year. 

There  is  a  certain  superficial  plausibility  in  the  method,  but  it 

is  easy  to  see  that  it  is  unsound,  for  it  takes  too  unfavourable  a  view 

of  human  life  after  the  eradication  of  small-pox.     For  let 

u^  +  ^^2  +  •  •  •  ^^r  =  ^r  > 

then  we  know  from  the  observations  that  at  the  end  of  r  years 
there  are  N  —U^—  V^  survivors  of  the  original  N  \  of  these  w.^^  die 
in  the  next  year  from  all  diseases  excluding  small-pox.  Thus 
excluding  small-pox 


^r+i 


N-U,-  V/ 


is  the  ratio  of  those  who  die  in  the  year  to  those  who  are  aged 
r  years  at  the  beginning  of  the  year.  And  this  ratio  will  be  the 
ratio  which  ought  to  hold  in  the  new  tables  of  mortality.  The 
method  of  the  savant  Geometre  gives  instead  of  this  ratio  the 
greater  ratio 


'•+1 


N-  U.- 


n 


488.  Thus  we  see  where  the  savant  Geometre  was  wrong,  and 
the  nature  of  the  error.  The  pages  in  D'Alembert  are  88 — 92 ; 
but  it  will  require  some  attention  to  extricate  the  false  principle 
really  used  from  the  account  which  D'Alembert  gives,  which  is  also 
obscured  by  a  figure  of  a  curve.  In  D'Alembert's  account  regard 
is  paid  to  the  circumstance  that  Inoculation  is  fatal  to  some  on 
whom  it  is  performed  ;  but  this  is  only  a  matter  of  detail :  the 
essential  principle  involved  is  that  which  we  have  here  exhibited. 

489.     The  next  publication  of  D'Alembert  on  the  subject  of 
Probabilities  appears  to  consist  of  some  remarks  in  his  Melanges 


272  d'alembert. 

de  Philosophie,  Vol.  v.  I  have  never  seen  the  original  edition  of 
this  work  ;  but  I  have  no  doubt  that  the  remarks  in  the  Melanges 
de  Philosopliie  were  those  which  are  reprinted  in  the  first  volume 
of  the  collected  edition  of  the  literary  and  philosophical  works  of 
D'Alembert,  in  5  Vols.  8vo,  Paris,  1821.  According  to  the  cita- 
tions of  some  writers  on  the  subject  I  conclude  that  these  remarks 
also  occur  in  the  fourth  volume  of  the  edition  of  the  literary  and 
philosophical  works  in  18  Vols.  8vo,  Paris,  1805. 

490.  In  the  first  volume  of  the  edition  of  1821  there  are  two 
essays,  one  on  the  general  subject  of  Probabilities,  and  the  other  on 
Inoculation. 

The  first  essay  is  entitled  Doutes  et  questions  sur  le  Calcul  des 
Prohahilites.  These  occupy  pages  451 — 466 ;  the  pages  being 
closely  printed. 

D'Alembert  commences  thus : 

On  se  plaint  assez  communement  que  les  formules  des  matli^ma- 
ticiens,  appliquees  aux  objets  de  la  nature,  ne  se  trouvent  que  trop 
en  defaut.  Personne  neanmoins  n'avait  encore  apergu  ou  cru  aper- 
cevoir  cet  inconvenient  dans  le  calcul  des  prohahilites.  J'ai  os6  le 
premier  proposer  des  doutes  sur  quelques  principes  qui  servent  de  base 
ii  ce  calcul.  De  grands  geometres  ont  juge  ces  doutes  dignes  d' attention; 
d'autres  grands  geometres  les  ont  trouves  ahsurdes;  car  pourquoi  adou- 
cirais-je  les  termes  dont  ils  se  sont  servis  ?  La  question  est  de  savoir 
s'ils  ont  eu  tort  de  les  employer,  et  en  ce  cas  ils  auraient  doublement 
tort.  Leur  decision,  qu'ils  n'ont  pas  juge  a  propos  de  motiver,  a  en- 
courage des  mathematiciens  mediocres,  qui  se  sont  hates  d'ecrire  sur  ce 
sujet,  et  de  m'attaquer  sans  m'entendre.  Je  vais  tacher  de  m'expliquer 
si  clairement,  que  presque  tous  mes  lecteurs  seront  a  portee  de  me 
jager. 

491.  The  essay  which  we  are  now  considering  may  be  described 

in   general   as   consisting   of  the   matter    in   the  second  volume 

of  the  Opuscides  divested  of  mathematical  formulae  and  so  adapted 

to  readers  less  versed  in   mathematics.      The   objections  against 

the  ordinary  theory  are  urged  perhaps  with  somewhat  less  con- 

2 
fidence ;   and    the    particular  case    in  which    -  was  proposed  in- 

3  . 

stead  of  7  ^s  the  result  in  an  elementary  question  does  not  appear. 

But  the  other  errors  are  all  retained. 


d'alembert.  273 

492.  There  is  some  additional  matter  in  the  essay.  D'Alem- 
bert  notices  the  calculation  of  Daniel  Bernoulli  relative  to  the 
small  inclination  to  the  ecliptic  of  the  orbits  of  the  planets ; 
see  Art.  394.  D'Alembert  considers  Daniel  Bernoulli's  result 
as  worthless. 

DAlembert  says  with  respect  to  Daniel  Bernoulli, 

Ce  qu'il  y  a  de  singulier,  c'est  que  ce  grand  geometre  dont  je  parle, 
a  trouve  ridicules,  du  moins  ^  ce  qu'on  m'assure,  mes  raisonnemens 
sur  le  calcul  des  2^Tobahilites. 

493.  D'Alembert  introduces  an  illustration  which  Laplace 
afterwards  adopted.  D'Alembert  supposes  that  we  see  on  a  table 
the  letters  which  form  the  word  Constantinojyolitanensibus,  ar- 
ranged in  this  order,  or  arranged  in  alphabetical  order  ;  and  he 
says  that  although  mathematically  these  distributions  and  a  third 
case  in  which  the  letters  follow  at  hazard  are  equally  possible, 
yet  a  man  of  sense  would  scarcely  doubt  that  the  first  or  second 
distribution  had  not  been  produced  by  chance.  See  Laplace, 
Theorie  . . .  des  Proh.  page  xi. 

494.  D'Alembert  quotes  the  article  Fatalite  in  the  Ency do- 
pe die,  as  supporting  him  at  least  partially  in  one  of  the  opinions 
which  he  maintained  ;  namely  that  which  we  have  noticed  in  the 
latter  part  of  our  Art.  474.  The  name  of  the  writer  of  the  article 
Fatalite  is  not  given  in  the  Encyclopedia. 

495.  The  other  essay  Avhich  we  find  in  the  first  volume 
of  the  edition  of  D'Alembert's  literary  and  philosophical  works 
of  1821,  is  entitled  Reflexions  sur  T Inoculation ;  it  occupies 
pages  463 — 514. 

In  the  course  of  the  preface  D'Alembert  refers  to  the  fourth 
volume  of  his  Opuscules.  The  fourth  volume  of  the  Opuscules  is 
dated  1768  ;  in  the  preface  to  it  D'Alembert  refers  to  his  Me- 
langes de  Philosophie,  Vol.  V. 

We  may  perhaps  infer  that  the  fifth  volume  of  the  Melanges.,, 
and  the  fourth  volume  of  the  Opuscules  appeared  at  about  the 
same  date. 

496.  The  essay  may  be  said  to  consist  of  the  same  matter 

18 


27^  d'alembert. 

as  appeared  on  the  subject  in  the  second  volume  of  the  Opuscules, 
omitting  the  mathematical  investigations,  but  expanding  and 
illustrating  all  the  rest. 

D'Alembert's  general  position  is  that  the  arguments  which 
have  hitherto  been  brought  forward  for  Inoculation  or  against  it 
are  almost  all  unsound.  His  own  reflexions  however  lead  to  the 
conclusion  that  Inoculation  is  advantageous,  and  that  conclusion 
seems  more  confidently  maintained  in  the  essay  than  in  the 
Opuscules.  Some  additional  facts  concerning  the  subject  are  re- 
ferred to  in  the  essay ;  they  had  probably  been  published  since 
the  second  volume  of  the  Opuscules. 

497.  D'Alembert  retains  the  opinion  he  had  formerly  held  as 
to  the  difficulty  of  an  exact  mathematical  solution  of  the  problem 
respecting  the  advantages  of  Inoculation.  He  says  in  summing 
up  his  remarks  on  this  point :  S'il  est  quelqu'un  a  qui  la  solution 
de  ce  probl^me  soit  reservee,  ce  ne  sera  st\rement  pas  a  ceux  qui 
la  croiront  facile. 

498.  D'Alembert  insists  strongly  on  the  want  of  ample  col- 
lections of  observations  on  the  subject.  He  wishes  that  medical 
men  would  keep  lists  of  all  the  cases  of  small-pox  which  come 
under  their  notice.     He  sa3"s, 

...ces  registres,  donnes  an  public  par  les  Facultes  de  medecine  ou 
par  les  particuliers,  seraient  certainement  d'une  utilite  plus  palpable 
et  plus  prochaine,  que  les  recueils  d'observations  meteorologiques  pub- 
lies  avec  tant  de  soin  par  nos  Academies  depuis  70  ans,  et  qui  pour- 
tant,  ^  certains  egards,  ne  sont  pas  eux-memes  sans  utilite. 

Combien  ne  serait-il  pas  a  souhaiter  que  les  medecins,  au  lieu  de 
se  quereller,  de  s'injurier,  de  se  dechirer  mutuellement  au  sujet  de 
I'inoculation  avec  un  aeharnement  tlieologique,  au  lieu  de  supposer 
ou  de  degniser  les  faits,  voulussent  bien  se  reunir,  pour  faire  de  bonne 
foi  toutes  les  experiences  necessaires  sur  une  matiere  si  interessante 
pour  la  vie  des  homrnes  ] 

499.  We  next  proceed  to  the  fourth  volume  of  D'Alemherfs 
Opuscules,  in  which  the  pages  73 — 105  and  283—341  are  de- 
voted to  our  subject.  The  remarks  contained  in  these  pages  are 
presented  as  extracts  from  letters. 


U^ALEMBERT.  275 

500,  We  will  now  take  the  first  of  the  two  portions,  which 
occupies  pages  73 — 105, 

D'Alembert  begins  with  a  section  Siir  le  calcul  des  Prohahilites. 
This  section  is  chiefly  devoted  to  the  Petersburg  Problem.     The 

chance   that   head  wdll   not   appear  before  the   n^^'   throw   is  ^ 

on  the  ordinary  theory.     D'Alembert  proposes  quite  arbitrarily  to 
change  this  expression  into  some  other  which  will  bring  out  a 

finite  result  for  ^'s  expectation.     He  suggests        , ^-^  where 

/8  is  a  constant.    In  this  case  the  summation  wdiich  the  problem  re- 

1 

quires  can  only  be  effected  approximately.    He  also  suggests    ^^^^^ 

id 

^^^d  „^^.a(»-i)  where  a  is  a  constant. 

He  gives  of  course  no  reason  for  these  suggestions,  except 
that  they  lead  to  a  finite  result  instead  of  the  infinite  result  of 
the  ordinary  theory.     But  his  most  curious  suggestion  is  that  of 

1  ^ 1 ,  where  B  and  K  are  constants 

and  17  an  odd  integer.     He  says, 

Nous  mettons  le  nombre  pair  2  au  denominateur  de  Texposant,  afiu 
que  quand  on  est  arrive  au  nombre  n  qui  donne  la  probabilite  ^gale 
a  zero,  on  ne  trouve  pas  la  probabilite  negative,  en  faisant  n  plus 
grand  que  ee  nombre,  ce  qui  seroit  clioquant ;  car  la  probabilite  ne 
sauroit  jamais  ^tre  au-dessous  de  zero,  II  est  vrai  qu'en  faisant  n 
plus  grand  que  le  nombre  dont  il  s'agit,  elle  devient  imaginaire;  mais 
cet  inconvenient  me  paroit  moindre  que  celui  de  devenir  negative;... 

501.  D'Alembert's  next  section  is  entitled  Bur  Tanalyse  des 
Jeux. 

D'Alembert  first  proposes  une  consideration  tr^s-simple  et 
tr^s-naturelle  a  faire  dans  le  calcul  des  jeux,  et  dont  M.  de  Buffon 
m'a  donne  la  premiere  idee,  . . .  This  consideration  we  will  explain 
when  noticing  a  w^ork  by  Buffon.  D'Alembert  gives  it  in  the 
form  which  Buffon  ought  to  have  given  it  in  order  to  do  justice 
to  his  own  argument.     But   soon  after  in  a  numerical  example 

18—2 


X 


276  d'alembert. 

D'Alembert  falls  back  on  Biiffon's  own  statement ;  for  he  supposes 
that  a  man  has  100000  crowns,  and  that  he  stakes  50000  at  an 
equal  game,  and  he  says  that  this  man's  damage  if  he  loses  is 
greater  than  his  advantage  if  he  gains ;  jDuisque  dans  le  premier 
cas,  il  s'appauvrira  de  la  moitie ;  et  que  dans  le  second,  il  ne 
s'enrichira  que  du  tiers. 

502.  If  a  person  has  the  chance  ■ of  gaining  x  and  the 

chance  — - —  of  losing  y,  his  expectation  on  the  ordinary  theory 

is  ~ ^ .     D'Alembert  obtains  this  result  himself  on  the  ordi- 

nary    principles ;    but   then    he   thinks    another    result,   namely 

—  ,  miofht  also  be  obtained  and  defended.     Let  jz  denote  the 

sum  which  a  man  should  give  for  the  privilege  of  being  placed 
in  the  position  stated.     If  he  gains  he  receives  x,  so  that  as  he 

paid  z  his  balance  is  x  —  z.     Thus  — is  the  correspondincj 

expectation.  If  he  loses,  as  he  has  already  paid  z  he  will  have 
to  pay  y  —  ^  additional,  so  that  his  total  loss  is  y,  and  his  con- 
sequent expectation  - — ^'^- .     Then  ^— — —  is  his  total  ex- 

p  -^  q  p  +  q 

pectation,  which    ought  to  be  zero  if  z  is  the  fair  sum  for  him 

to  pay.     Thus  z  =  ^ ^^  .     It  is  almost  superfluous  to  observe 

that  the  words  which  we  have  printed  in  Italics  amount  to  as- 
signing a  new  meaning  to  the  problem.  Thus  D'Alembert  gives 
us  not  two  discordant  solutions  of  the  sa77ie  problem,  but  solu- 
tions of  two  different  problems.  See  his  further  remarks  on  his 
page  283. 

503.  D'Alembert  objects  to  the  common  rule  of  multiplying 
the  value  to  be  obtained  by  the  probability  of  obtaining  it  in 
order  to  determine  the  expectation.  He  thinks  that  the  pro- 
bability is  the  principal  element,  and  the  value  to  be  obtained 
is  subordinate.  He  brings  the  following  example  as  an  objection 
against  the  ordinary  theory;  but  his  meaning  is  scarcely  intel- 
ligible : 


N 


d'alembert.  277 

Qu'on  propose  de  choisir  entre  100  combinaisons,  dont  99  feroiit 
gagner  mille  ecus,  et  la  100®  99  mille  ecus;  quel  sera  I'liomme  assez 
iusense  pour  preferer  celle  qui  donnera  99  mille  ecus.  Uesperance  dans 
les  deux  cas  n'est  done  pas  reellement  la  meme;  quoiqu'elle  soit  la 
meme  suivant  les  regies  des  probabilites. 

504^.  D'Alembert  appeals  to  the  authority  of  Pascal,  in  the 
following  words  : 

Un  homme,  dit  Pascal,  passeroit  pour  fou,  s'il  hesitoit  a  so  laisser 
donner  la  mort  en  cas  qu'avec  trois  dez  on  fit  vingt  fois  de  suite  trois 
six,  ou  d'etre  Empereur  si  on  y  manquoit  ?  Je  pense  absolument  comme 
lui  j  mais  pourquoi  cet  homme  passeroit-il  pour  fou,  si  le  cas  dont  il 
s'agit,  est  'pliysiquement  j)ossible  % 

See  too  the  edition  of  D'Alembert's  literary  and  philosophical 
works,  Paris,  1821,  Vol.  I.  page  553,  note. 

505.  The  next  section  is  entitled  8ur  la  duree  de  la  vie. 
D'Alembert  draws  attentioD  to  the  distinction  between  the  mean 
duration  of  life  and  the  probable  duration  of  life  ;  see  Art.  484. 
D'Alembert  seems  to  think  it  is  a  great  objection  to  the  Theory 
of  Probabihty  that  there  is  this  distinction. 

D'Alembert's  objection  to  the  Theory  of  Probability  is  as 
reasonable  as  an  objection  to  the  Theory  of  Mechanics  would  be 
on  the  ground  that  the  centre  of  gi'avity  of  an  area  does  not 
necessarily  fall  on  an  assigned  line  which  bisects  the  area. 

D'Alembert  asserts  that  a  numerical  statement  of  Buffon's, 
which  Daniel  Bernoulli  had  suspected  of  inaccuracy,  was  not  really 
inaccurate,  but  that  the  difference  between  Buffon  and  Daniel 
Bernoulli  arose  from  the  distinction  between  what  we  call  meaii 
duration  and  probable  duration  of  life. 

506.  The  last  section  is  entitled  Sur  un  Memoire  de  M.  Ber- 
noulli concernant  F Inoculation. 

Daniel  Bernoulli  in  the  commencement  of  his  memoir  had 
said,  il  seroit  a  souhaiter  que  les  critiques  fussent  plus  reserves 
et  plus  circonspects,  et  sur-tout  qu'ils  se  donnassent  la  peine  de  se 
mettre  au  fait  des  choses  qu'ils  se  proposent  d'avance  de  critiquer. 
The  words  se  mettre  au  fait  seem  to  have  given  great  offence  to 


»'=7C'  -tn' 


27S  D  ALEMBEllT. 

D'Alembert  as  he  supposed  they  were  meant  for  him.  He  refers 
to  them  in  the  Opuscules,  Vol.  IV.  pages  IX,  99,  100 ;  and  he 
seems  with  ostentatious  deference  to  speak  of  Daniel  Bernoulli 
as  ce  grand  Geometre;  see  pages  99,  101,  315,  821,  323  of  the 
volume, 

507.  D'Alembert  objects  to  the  hypotheses  on  which  Daniel 
Bernoulli  had  based  his  calculation ;  see  Art.  401.  D'Alembert 
brings  forward  another  objection  which  is  quite  fallacious,  and 
which  seems  to  shew  that  his  vexation  had  disturbed  his  judg- 
ment. Daniel  Bernoulli  had  found  that  the  average  life  of  all 
who  die  of  small-pox  is  6^^  years ;  and  that  if  small-pox  were 
extinguished  the  average  human  life  would  be  29^^  years.  More- 
over the  average  human  life  subject  to  small-pox  is  26^^  years. 
Also   Daniel  Bernoulli  admitted   that   the   deaths   by  small-pox 

were  —  ^^  ^^^  ^^®  deaths, 

J-O 

Hence  D'Alembert  affirms  that  the  folloAving  relation  ought 

to  hold; 

1  12 

but  the  relation  does  not  hold;  for  the  terms  on  the  left  hand  side 
will  give  27{^  nearly  instead  of  263^.  D'Alembert  here  makes  the 
mistake  which  1  have  pointed  out  in  Art.  487 ;  when  that  Article 
was  written,  I  had  not  read  the  remarks  by  D'Alembert  which 
are  now  under  discussion,  but  it  appeared  to  me  that  D'Alembert 
was  not  clear  on  the  point,  and  the  mistake  which  he  now  makes 
confirms  my  suspicion. 

To  make  the  above  equation  correct  we  must  remove  29^, 
and  j)ut  in  its  place  the  average  duration  of  those  who  die  of 
other  diseases  while  small-pox  still  prevails ;  this  number  will  be 
smaller  than  29j^2' 

508.  We  pass  on  to  the  pages  283—341  of  the  fourth  volume 
of  the  Opuscules.  Here  we  have  two  sections,  one  Sur  le  Calcul 
des  probahilites,  the  other  Sur  les  Calculs  relatifs  a  I' Inoculation, 

609.     The  first  section  consists  of  little  more  than  a  repetition 


D  ALEMBEllT.  279 

of  the  remarks  which    have  akeady  been  noticed.     D'Alembei-t 
records  the  origin  of  his  doubts  in  these  words  : 

II  y  a  pres  de  trente  ans  que  j'avois  forme  ces  doutes  en  Hsaiit 
Texcellent  livre  de  M.  BernoulU  de  Arte  conjectandi ; . . . 

He  seems  to  have  returned  to  his  old  error  respecting  Croix 
ou  Pile  with  fresh  ardour  :  he  says, 

...si  les  trois  cas,  croix,  pile  et  croix,  pile  et  2^ile,  les  seuls  qui 
puissent  arriver  dans  le  jeu  propose,  ne  sont  pas  egalement  possibles, 
ce  n'est  point,  ce  me  semble,  par  la  raison  qu'on  en  apporte  commu- 

nement,  que  la  probabilite  du  premier  est  -  ,    et  celle  des  deux  autres 

Q  X  -  ou  -  .     Plus  j'y  pense,  et  plus  il  me  paroit  que  Tiiathematique- 
nient  parlaut,  ces  trois  coups  sont  egalement  possibles... 

510.  D'Alembert  introduces  another  point  in  which  he  ob- 
jects to  a  principle  commonly  received.  He  will  not  admit  that 
it  is  the  same  thing  to  toss  one  coin  m  times  in  succession,  or 
to  toss  m  coins  simultaneously.  He  says  it  is  perhaps  physically 
speaking  more  possible  to  have  the  same  face  occurring  simul- 
taneously an  assigned  number  of  times  with  m  coins  tossed  at 
once,  than  to  have  the  same  face  repeated  the  same  assigned 
number  of  times  when  one  coin  is  tossed  ')n  times.  But  no  person 
will  allow  what  D'Alembert  states.  We  can  indeed  suppose  circum- 
stances in  which  the  two  cases  are  not  quite  the  same  ;  for  example 
if  the  coins  used  are  not  perfectly  symmetrical,  so  that  they 
have  a  tendency  to  fall  on  one  face  rather  than  on  the  other. 
But  we  should  in  such  a  case  expect  a  run  of  resemblances  rather 
in  using  one  coin  for  m  throws,  than  in  using  m  coins  at  once. 
Take  for  a  simple  example  m  —  2.     We  should  have  rather  more 

than  -r  as  the  chance  for  the  former  result,  and  only  -  lor  tlie 

latter;  see  Laplace,  Theorie...des  Proh.  page  402. 

511.  D'Alembert  says  on  his  page  290,  II  y  a  quelque  temps 
qu'un  Joueur  me  demanda  en  combien  de  coups  consecutifs  on 
pouvoit  parier  avec  avantage  d'amener  une  face  donnee  d'un  de — 
This  is  the   old  question  proposed  to  Pascal  by  the  Chevalier  de 


280  d'alembert. 

Mere.  D'Alembert  answered  that  according  to  the  common  theory 
in  n  trials,  the  odds  would  be  as  &"  —  5"  to  5".  Thus  there  would 
be  advantage  in  undertaking  to  do  it  in  four  throws.  Then 
D'Alembert  adds,  Ce  Joueur  me  repondit  que  Texperience  lui  avoit 
para  contraire  a  ce  resultat,  et  qu'en  jouant  quatre  coups  de 
suite  pour  amener  une  face  donnee,  il  lui  etoit  arrive  beaucoup 
plus  souvent  de  gagner  que  de  perdre.  D'Alembert  says  that 
if  this  be  true,  the  disagreement  between  theory  and  observation 
may  arise  from  the  fact  that  the  former  rests  on  a  supposition 
which  he  has  before  stated  to  be  false.  Accordingly  D'Alembert 
points  out  that  on  his  principles  the  number  of  favourable  cases 
in  n  throws  instead  of  being  6"  —  5^  as  by  the  ordinary  theory, 
would  be  1  +  5  +  5^4-...  +  5'^~\  This  is  precisely  analogous  to  what 
we  have  given  for  a  die  with  three  faces  in  Art.  477.  D'Alembert 
however  admits  that  we  must  not  regard  all  these  cases  as  equally 
likely. 

512.  D'Alembert  quotes  testimonies  in  his  own  favour  from  the 
letters  of  three  mathematicians  to  himself;  see  his  pages  296,  297. 
One  of  these  correspondents  he  calls,  un  tr^s-profond  et  trt^s-habile 
Analyste  ;  another  he  calls,  un  autre  Mathematicien  de  la  plus 
grande  reputation  et  la  mieux  meritee  ;  and  the  third,  un  autre 
Ecrivain  tres-eclaire,  qui  a  cultive  les  Mathematiques  avec  succ^s, 
et  qui  est  connu  par  un  excellent  Ouvrage  de  Philosophie.  But 
this  Ecrivain  tres-dclaire  is  a  proselyte  whose  zeal  is  more  con- 
spicuous than  his  judgment.  He  says  "ce  que  vous  dites  sur  la 
probabilite  est  excellent  et  trer-evident ;  I'ancien  calcul  des  pro- 
babilitcs  est  ruine  . . .  D'Alembert  is  obliged  to  add  in  a  note, 
Je  n'en  demande  pas  tant,  a  beaucoup  pres  ;  je  ne  pretends  point 
ruiner  le  calcul  des  probabilites,  je  desire  seulement  qu'il  soit 
eclairci  et  modifie. 

513.  D'Alembert  returns  to  the  Petersburg  Problem.  He 
says, 

Yous  dites,  Monsieur,  que  la  raison  pour  laqiielle  on  trouve  I'enjeu 
infini,  c'est  la  supposition  tacite  qu'on  fait  que  le  jeu  peut  avoir 
une  duree  infinie,  ce  que  n'est  pas  admissible,  attendu  que  la  vie  des 
hommes  ne  dure  qu'un  temps. 


d'alembert.  281 

D'Alembert  brings  forward  four  remarks  which  shew  that  thi^ 
mode  of  explaining  the  difficulty  is  unsatisfactory.  One  of  theoi 
is  the  following :  instead  of  supposing  that  one  crown  is  to  be 
received  for  head  at  the  first  throw,  two  for  head  at  the  second 
throw,  four  for  head  at  the  third  throw,  and  so  on,  suppose  that  in 
each  case  only  one  crown  is  to  be  received.  Then,  although  theo- 
retically the  game  may  endure  to  infinity,  yet  the  value  of  the 
expectation  is  finite.  This  remark  may  be  said  to  contradict  a 
conclusion  at  which  D'Alembert  arrived  in  his  article  Croix  oil 
Pile,  which  we  noticed  in  Ai"t.  ^^d. 

51-i.  The  case  just  brought  forward  is  interesting  because 
D'Alembert  admits  that  it  might  supply  an  objection  to  his  prin- 
ciples. He  tries  to  repel  the  objection  by  saying  that  it  only  leads 
him  to  suspect  another  principle  of  the  ordinary  theory,  namely 
that  in  virtue  of  which  the  total  expectation  is  taken  to  be  equal 
to  the  sum  of  the  partial  expectations ;  see  his  pages  299 — 301. 

* 

515.  D'Alembert  thus  sums  up  his  objections  against  the 
ordinary  theory : 

Pour  resumer  en  un  mot  tons  ines  doutes  sur  le  calcul  des  pro- 
babilites,  et  les  mettre  sous  les  yeux  des  vrais  Juges;  voici  ce  que 
j'accorde  et  ce  que  je  nie  dans  les  raisonnemens  explicites  ou  implicites 
sur  lesquels  ce  calcul  me  paroit  fonde. 

Premier  raisonnement.  Le  u  ombre  des  combinaisons  qui  amenent 
tel  cas,  est  au  nombre  des  combinaisons  qui  amenent  tel  autre  cas, 
comme  p  est  ^  q.  Je  conviens  de  cette  verite  qui  est  purement  ma- 
thematique;  done,  conclut-on,  la  probabilite  du  premier  cas  est  a  celle 
du  second  comme  j^  est  a  q.  Yoila  ce  que  je  nie,  ou  du  moins  de 
quoi  je  doute  fort;  et  je  crois  que  si,  par  exemple,  ^^  =  5',  et  que  dans 
le  second  cas  Je  meme  evenement  se  trouve  un  tres-grand  nombre  de 
fois  de  suite,  il  sera  moins  probable  physiquement  que  le  premier, 
quoique  les  probabilites  mathematiques  soient  egales. 

Second  raisonnement.  LaprobabiUte  -  est  a  la  probabilite  —  comme 

^  m  n 

np  ecus  est  a  mp  ecus.    J'en  conviens;  done—  x  mp  ecus  =  -  x  np  ecus; 

j'en  conviens  encore;    done  Vesperance,   ou  ce  qui  est  la  meme  chose, 


282  d'alembert. 

le   sort    d'un   Joueur   qui    aura    la    probabilite    —  de  gagner  mp  ecus, 

sera    egale  a  I'esperance,  au  sort  d'un  Joueur  qui  aura  la  probabilite 

1 

-  de  gagner  np  ecus.     Yoila  ce  que  je  nie;  je  dis  que  Vesperaiice  est 

it 

plus    grande    pour    celui  qui  a  la  plus   grande  probabilite,   quoique  la 
somme  esperee  soit  moindre,  et  qu'on  ne  doit  pas  balancer  de  preferer 

le  sort  d'un    Joueur  qui  a  la  probabilite  -  de  gagner  1000   ecus,  au 

sort  d'un  Joueur  qui  a  la  probabilite  ^ttftt.  d'en  gagner  1000000. 

Trolsieme  raisonnement  qui  nest  qiiimplicite.  Soit  p  +  q  le  nombre 
total  des  cas,  2^  1^  j^robabilite  d'un  certain  nombre  de  cas,  q  la  proba- 
bilite des  autres;  la  probabilite  de  cliacun  sera  a  la  certitude  totale, 
comme  p  et  q  sont  k p  +  q.  Viola  ce  que  je  nie  encore;  je  conviens, 
ou  plutot  j'accorde,  que  les  probabilites  de  cliaque  cas  sont  comme  p 
et  q ;  je  conviens  qu'il  arrivera  certainement  et  infailliblement  un 
des  cas  dont  le  nombre  est  jy  +  q',  mais  je  nie  que  du  rapport  des  pro- 
babilites entr'elies,  on  puisse  en  conclure  leur  rapport  a  la  certitude 
absolue,  parce  que  la  certitude  absolue  est  infinie  par  ra^iport  a  la  plus 
grande  probabilite. 

Vous  me  demanderez  peut-etre  quels  sont  les  principes  qu'il  faut, 
selon  moi,  substituer  a  ceux  dont  je  revoque  en  doute  I'exactitude  ?  Ma 
reponse  sera  celle  que  j'ai  deja  faite;  je  n'en  sais  rien,  et  je  suis  meme 
tres-porte  a  croii'e  que  la  matiere  dont  il  s'agit,  ne  peut  etre  soumise, 
au  moins  a  plusieurs  egards,  a  un  calcul  exact  et  precis,  egalement  net 
dans  ses  principes  et  dans  ses  resultats. 

516.  D'Alembert  now  returns  to  the  calculations  relating  to 
Inoculation.  He  criticises  very  minutely  the  mathematical  in- 
vestigations of  Daniel  Bernoulli. 

The  objection  which  D'Alembert  first  urges  is  as  follows.  •  Let 
s  be  the  number  of  persons  alive  at  the  commencement  of  the 

SOi'JC 

time  X ;  then  Daniel  Bernoulli  assumes  that  — -r-  die  from  small- 

pox  during  the  time  dx.     Therefore  the  whole  number  who  die 
from  small-pox  during  the   (n  -f- 1)*^  year  is 


f 


""^^  sdx 


d'alembeht.  2bo 

S 
But  this  is  not   the   same   thing  as   7,-7 ,   where   S  denotes   the 

number  aUve  at  the  beginning  of  the  year ;  for  s  is  a  variable 
gradually  diminishing  during  the  year  from  the   value   S  with 

which  it  began.      But  ^7  ^^  ^^^  result  which  Daniel  Bernoulli 

professed  to  take  from  observation ;  therefore  Daniel  Bernoulli  is 
inconsistent  with  himself.  D'Alembert's  objection  is  sound  ;  Daniel 
Bernoulli  would  no  doubt  have  admitted  it,  and  have  given  the 
just  reply,  namely  that  his  calculations  only  professed  to  be 
approximately  correct,  and  that  they  were  approximately  correct. 

Moreover  the  error  arising  in  taking  sdx  and  S  to  be  equal  in 

value  becomes  very  small  if  we  suppose  S  to  be,  not  the  value  of 

s  when  x  =  7i  ov  n  +  1  but,  the  intermediate  value  when  x  =  n  -\-  -^  ; 

and  nothing  in  Daniel  Bernoulli's  investigation  forbids  this  sup- 
position. 

517.  We  have  put  the  objection  in  the  preceding  Article  as 
D'Alembert  ought  to  have  put  it  in  fairness.  He  himself  however 
really  assumes  n  =  0,  so  that  his  attack  does  not  strictly  fall  on  the 
whole  of  Daniel  Bernoulli's  table  but  on  its  first  line  ;  see  Art.  403. 
This  does  not  affect  the  principle  on  which  DAlembert's  objection 
rests,  but  taken  in  conjunction  with  the  remarks  in  the  preceding 
Article,  it  will  be  found  to  diminish  the  practical  value  of  the  ob- 
jection considerably.     See  D'Alembert's  pages  312 — 314. 

618.  Another  objection  which  D'Alembert  takes  is  also  sound  ; 
see  his  page  315.  It  amounts  to  saying  that  instead  of  using  the 
Differential  Calculus  Daniel  Bernoulli  ought  to  have  used  the 
Calculus  of  Finite  Differences.  We  have  seen  in  Art.  417  that 
Daniel  Bernoulli  proposed  to  solve  various  problems  in  the  Theory 
of  Probability  by  the  use  of  the  Differential  Calculus.  The  reply 
to  be  made  to  D'Alembert's  objection  is  that  Daniel  Bernoulli's 
investigation  accomplishes  what  was  proposed,  namely  an  approxi- 
mate solution  of  the  problem  ;  we  shall  however  see  hereafter  in 
examining  a  memoir  by  Trembley  that,  assuming  the  In^otheses  of 
Daniel  Bernoulli,  a  solution  by  common  algebra  might  be  effected. 


28  i  d'alembert.  - 

519.  D'Alembert  thinks  that  Daniel  Bernoulli  might  have 
solved  the  problem  more  simply  and  not  less  accurately.  For 
Daniel  Bernoulli  made  two  assumptions  ;  see  Art.  401.  D'Alembert 
says  that  only  one  is  required ;  namely  to  assume  some  function 
of  y  for  u  in  Art.  483.  Accordingly  D'Alembert  suggests  arbi- 
trarily some  functions,  which  have  apparently  far  less  to  recom- 
mend them  as  corresponding  to  facts,  than  the  assumptions  of 
Daniel  Bernoulli. 

520.  D'Alembert  solves  what  he  calls  un  prohleme  assez  cu- 

rieux ;  see  his  page  325.    He  solves  it  on  the  assumptions  of  Daniel 

Bernoulli,  and  also  on  his  own.     We  wdll  give  the  former  solution. 

Return  to  Art.  402  and  suppose  it  required  to  determine  out  of 

the  number  s  the  number  of  those  who  will  die  by  the  small-pox. 

Let  ft)  denote  the  number  of  those  who  do  not  die  of  small-pox. 

Hence  out  of  this  number  w  during  the   time  dx  none  will  die 

of  small-pox,  and  the  number  of  those  who  die  of  other  diseases 

/  sdx\  ft) 

will  be,  on  the  assumptions  of  Daniel  Bernoulli,  [  —  d^  — 


Hence,  —  dco  =  (—  d^  — 


mnj  ^  * 

sdx\   ft) 
mnJ   f  ' 


,1        r  dco      dP      sdx 

thereiore  —  =  —34.  - — . . 

Substitute  the  value  of  s  in  terms  of  x  and  |  from  Art.  402, 
and  integrate.     Thus  we  obtain 

X 

ft)  Ce" 


^       e"  (/>^  -  1)  +  1 


where  C  is  an  arbitrary  constant.  The  constant  may  be  deter- 
mined by  taking  a  result  which  has  been  deduced  from  observa- 
tion, namely  that   ^  =  97  when  a?  =  0. 


521.  D'Alembert  proposes  on  his  pages  326 — 328  the  method 
which  according  to  his  view  should  be  used  to  find  the  value  of 
s  at  the  time  x,  instead  of  the  method  of  Daniel  Bernoulli  which 


d'alembeet.  285 

we  gave  in  Art.  402.  D'Alembert's  method  is  too  arbitrary  in 
its  hypotheses  to  be  of  any  value. 

522.  D'Alembert  proposes  to  develop  his  refutation  of  the 
Savant  Geometre  whom  we  introduced  in  Art.  487.  He  shews 
decisively  that  this  person  was  wrong  ;  but  it  does  not  seem  to 
me  that  he  shews  distinctly  Jiow  he  was  wrong. 

523.  D'Alembert  devotes  the  last  ten  pages  of  the  memoir 
to  the  development  of  his  own  theory  of  the  mode  of  comparing 
the  risk  of  an  individual  if  he  undergoes  Inoculation  with  his 
risk  if  he  declines  it.  We  have  already  given  in  Art.  482,  a  hint 
of  DAlembert's  views ;  his  remarks  in  the  present  memoir  are 
ingenious  and  interesting,  but  as  may  be  supposed,  his  h}^otheses 
are  too  arbitrary  to  allow  any  practical  value  to  his  investiga- 
tions. 

524.  Two  remarks  which  he  makes  on  the  curve  of  mortality 
may  be  reproduced ;  see  his  page  840.  It  appears  from  Buffon''s 
tables  that  the  mean  duration  of  life  for  persons  aged  n  years 

1 

is  always  less  than  ^  (100  —  n).     Hence,  taking  100  years  as  the 

extreme  duration  of  human  life,  it  will  follow  that  the  curve  of 
mortality  cannot  be  always  concave  to  the  axis  of  abscissse.  Also 
from  the  tables  of  Buffon  it  follows  that  the  pivhahle  duration 
of  life  is  almost  always  greater  than  the  mean  duration.  D'Alem- 
bert applies  this  to  shew  that  the  curve  of  mortality  cannot  be 
always  convex  to  the  axis  of  abscissae. 

525.  The  fifth  volume  of  the  Opuscules  was  published  in 
1768.  It  contains  two  brief  articles  with  which  we  are  con- 
cerned. 

Pages  228 — 231  are  Bur  les  Tables  de  mortalite.  The  numeri- 
cal results  are  given  which  served  for  the  foundation  of  the  two 
remarks  noticed  in  Art.  524. 

Pages  508 — 510  are  Sur  les  calculs  relatifs  d  V inoculation.,. 
These  remarks  form  an  addition  to  the  memoir  in  pages  283 — 341 
of  the  fourth  volume  of  the  Opuscules.  D'Alembert  notices  a  reply 
which  had  been  offered  to  one  of  his  objections,   and  enforces  the 


28(>  d'alembeut, 

justness  of  his  objections.  Nevertheless  he  gives  his  reasons  for 
regarding  Inoculation  as  a  useful  practice. 

526.  The  seventh  and  eighth  volume  of  the  Opuscules  were 
published  in  1780.  D'Alembert  says  in  an  Advertisement  pre- 
fixed to  the  seventh  volume,  ''...  Ce  seront  vraisemblablement,  ^ 
peu  de  chose  pr^s,  mes  derniers  Ouvrages  Mathematiques,  ma  tete, 
fatiguee  par  quarante-cinq  annees  de  travail  en  ce  genre,  n'etant 
plus  gu^re  capable  des  profondes  recherches  qu'il  exige."  D'Alem- 
bert  died  in  1788.  It  would  seem  according  to  his  biographers 
that  he  suffered  more  from  a  broken  heart  than  an  exhausted 
brain  during  the  last  few  years  of  his  life. 

527.  The  seventh  volume  of  the  Opuscules  contains  a  memoir 
Sur  le  calcul  des  Prohahilites,  which  occupies  pages  39 — 60.  We 
shall  see  that  D'Alembert  still  retained  his  objections  to  the 
ordinary  theory.     He  begins  thus  : 

Je  demande  pardon  aux  Geometres  de  revenir  encore  sur  ce  sujet. 
Mais  j'avoue  que  j)lus  j'y  ai  pense,  plus  je  me  suis  confirme  dans  mes 
<k>utes  sur les  principes  de  la  theorie  ordinaire;  je  desire  qu' on  eclaircisse 
ces  doutes,  et  que  cette  tlieorie,  soit  qu'on  y  change  quelques  principes, 
soit  qu'on  la  conserve  telle  qu'elle  est,  soit  du  moins  exposee  desormais 
de  maniere  a  ne  plus  laisser  aucuii  nnage. 

528.  We  will  not  delay  on  some  repetition  of  the  old  remarks  ; 
but  merely  notice  what  is  new.  We  find  on  page  42  an  error  which 
D'Alembert  has  not  exhibited  elsewhere,  except  in  the  article 
Cartes   in   the   Encyclopedie   Methodique,    which  we  shall   notice 

hereafter.     He  says  that  taking  two  throws  there  is  a  chance  ^  of 

1  -^ 

head  at  the  first  throw,  and  a  chance  -    of   head  at  the  second 

2 

throw  ;  and  thus  he  infers  that  the  chance  that  head  will  arrive  at 

least  once  is  -  +-^  or  1.     He  says  then,  Or  je  demande  si  cela  est 

vrai,  ou  du  moins  si  un  pareil  r^sultat,  fonde  sur  de  pareils  prin- 
cipes, est  bien  propre  a  satisfaire  I'esprit,  The  answer  is  that  the 
result  is  false,  being  erroneously  deduced  :  the  error  is  exposed  in 
elementary  works  on  the  subject. 

529.  The  memoir  is  chiefly  devoted  to  the  Petersburg  Problem. 
D'Alembert  refers  to  the  memoir  in  Yol.  vi.  of  the  Memoires...par 


d'alembeht.  287 

divers  Savans...  in  which  Laplace  had  made  the  supposition  that 
the  coin  has  a  gTeater  tendency  to  fall  on  one  side  than  the  other, 
but  it  is  not  known  on  which  side.  Suppose  that  2  crowns  are  to 
be  received  for  head  at  the  first  trial,  4  for  head  at  the  second, 
8  for  head  at  the  third,  . . .  Then  Laplace  shews  that  if  the  game  is 
to  last  for  X  trials  the  player  ought  to  give  to  his  antagonist  less 
than  X  crowns  if  x  be  less  than  5,  and  more  than  x  crowns  if  x  be 
greater  than  5,  and  just  x  crow^ns  if  x  be  equal  to  5.  On  the  com- 
mon hj^pothesis  he  would  always  have  to  give  x  crowns.  These 
results  of  Laplace  are  only  obtained  by  him  as  approximations  ; 
D'Alembert  seems  to  present  them  as  if  they  were  exact. 

530.     Suppose  the  probability  that  head  should  fall  at  first  to 

be  ft)  and  not  ^  ;  and  let  the  game  have  to  extend  over  n  trial  s 

Then  if  2  crowns  are  to  be  received  for  head  at  the  first  trial,  4 
for  head  at  the  second,  and  so  on ;  the  sum  which  the  player 
ouQ:ht  to  orive  is 

2(o  ;i  +  2  (1  -  ft))  +  2^  (1  -  ft>)^  +  ...  +  2"-^  (1  -  ft))"-'}, 

which  we  will  call  H. 

D'Alembert  suggests,  if  I  understand  him  rightly,  that  if  we 
know  nothing  about  the  value  of  co  we  may  take  as  a  solution  of 

the  problem,  for  the  sum  which  the  player  ought  to  give   I   fldo). 

But  this  involves  all  the  difficulty  of  the  ordinary  solution,  for  the 
result  is  infinite  wdien  n  is.  D'Alembert  is  however  very  obscure 
here  ;  see  his  pages  45,  46. 

He  seems  to  say  that  I  Cldco  will  be  greater  than,  equal  to,  or 

•^  0 

less  than  ??,  according  as  n  is  greater  than,  equal  to,  or  less  than  5. 
But  this  result  is  false  ;  and  the  argument  unintelligible  or  incon- 

elusive.     We  may  easily  see  by  calculation  that  I  D-dw  =  n  when 

n  =  l\    and   that   for    any   value    of    n   from    2    to    6    inclusive 

I  Hc^ft)  is  less  than  n  ;  and  that  when  n  is  7  or  any  greater  number 


0 

1 


I  Q.du>  is  greater  than  n. 

'   0 


288  d'alembert. 

531.  D'Alembert  then  proposes  a  method  of  solving  the  Peters- 
hiirg  Prohlem  which  shall  avoid  the  infinite  result ;  this  method  is 
perfectly  arbitrary.     He  says,  if  tail  has  arrived  at  the  first  throw, 

let  the  chance  that   head  arrives  at  the  next  be      ^     ,  and  not 

2 

- ,  where  a  is  some  small  quantity ;  if  tail  has  arrived  at  the  first 
throw,  and  at  the  second,  let  the  chance  that  head  arrives  at  the 

next  throw  be  ^ ,  and  not  ^ ;  if  tail  has  arrived  at  the  first 

throw,  at  the  second,  and  at  the  third,  let  the  chance  that  head 

arrives  at  the  next  throw  be — ,  and  not  -  ;  and  so  on. 

^  Ji 

The  quantities  a,  h,  c,  ...  are  supposed  small  positive  quantities, 
and  subjected  to  the  limitation  that  their  sum  is  less  than  unity, 
so  that  every  chance  may  be  less  than  unity. 

On  this  supposition  if  the  game  be  as  it  is  described  in  Art.  389, 
it  may  be  shewn  that  A  ought  to  give  half  of  the  following  series  : 

1 

+  (!+«) 

-f  (1  -  a)  (1  +  a  +  ^) 

+  (1  -  «)  (1  -  a  -  Z>)  (1  +  a  +  Z>  +  c) 

■^(l-a){l-  a-h-c)  {l  +  a-\-h  +  c-\-d) 

+ 

It  is  easily  shewn  that  this  is  finite.     For 

(1)  Each  of  the  factors  1+a,  \  -\-a-\-h,  l  +  a  +  Z>+c,  ...is  less 
than  2. 

(2)  \  —  a  —  h  is  less  than  1  —  a\ 

1  —  a  —  5  —  c  is  less  than  1  —  a  —  h,  and  a  fortiori  less  than 
1  — a ; 

and  so  on. 

Thus  the  series  excluding  the  first  two  terms  is  less  than  the 
Geometrical  Progression 

2  {1  -  a  +  (1  -  a)^  -f  (1  -  ay  +  (1  _  a)\ . .), 
and  is  therefore  finite. 


d'alembert.  289 

This  is  D'Alembert's  principle,  only  he  uses  it  thus:  he  shews 
that  all  the  terms  beginning  with 

are  less  than 

2{l-a){l-a-'h){l-a'-h'-e){l-a-h-c-d)s, 
where  s  denotes  the  geometrical  progression 

r  being  =  l^a  —  b-c  —  d.  * 

532.  Thus  on  his  arbitrary  hypotheses  D'Alembert  obtains  a 
finite  result  instead  of  an  infinite  result.  Moreover  he  performs 
what  appears  a  work  of  supererogation ;  for  he  shews  that  the  suc- 
cessive terms  of  the  infinite  series  which  he  obtains  form  a  con- 
tinually  diminishing  series  beginning  from  the  second,  if  we  suppose 
that  a,  h,Cjd,  ...  are  connected  by  a  certain  law  which  he  gives, 
namely, 

where  p  is  a  small  fraction,  and  m  —  1  is  the  number  of  the  quan- 
tities a,  h,  c,  d,  e,  ,..  Again  he  shews  that  the  same  result  holds  if 
we  merely  assume  that  a,h,c,d,e...  form  a  continually  diminish- 
ing series.  We  say  that  this  appears  to  be  a  work  of  supereroga- 
tion for  D'Alembert,  because  we  consider  that  the  infinite  result 
Avas  the  only  supposed  difficulty  in  the  Petersburg  Problem,  and 
that  it  was  sufficient  to  remove  this  without  shewing  that  the 
series  substituted  for  the  ordinary  series  consisted  of  terms  con- 
tinually decreasing.  But  D'Alembert  apparently  thought  differ- 
ently ;  for  after  demonstrating  this  continual  decrease  he  says, 

En  voila  assez  pour  faire  voir  que  les  termes  de  Tenjeu  vont  en 
diininuant  des  le  troisieme  coup,  jusqu'au  dernier.  Nous  avons  prouve 
d'ailleurs  que  I'enjeu  total,  somme  de  ces  termes,  est  fini,  en  supposant 
meme  le  nombre  de  coups  infini.  Ainsi  le  resultat  de  la  solution  que 
nous  donnons  ici  du  probleme  de  Petersbourg,  n'est  pas  sujet  a  la  diffi- 
culte  insoluble  des  solutions  ordinaires. 

583.  We  have  one  more  contrilnition  of  D'Alembert's  to  our 
subject  to  notice;    it  contains  errors  which  seem  extraordinary, 

19 


290  d'alembert. 

even  for  him.     It  is  the  article  Cartes  in  the  Encyclo^edie  Metho- 
dique.     The  following  problem  is  given, 

Pierre  tient  huit  cartes  dans  ses  mains  qui  sont :  tin  as,  lin  deux, 
un  trois,  im  quatre,  un  cinq,  un  six,  un  sept  et  un  huit,  qu'il  a  melees : 
Paul  parie  que  les  tirant  Tune  apres  I'autre,  il  les  devinera  k  mesure 
qu'il  les  tirera.  L'on  demande  combien  Pierre  doit  parier  centre  un 
que  Paul  ne  reussira  pas  dans  son  enterprise "? 

It  is  correctly  determined  that  Paul's  chance  is 

1111111 

Then  follow  three  problems  formed  on  this ;  the  whole  is  ab- 
surdly false.     We  give  the  words  : 

Si  Paul  parioit  d'amener  ou  de  deviner  juste  a  un  des  sept  coups 

.11  1 

seulement,   son     esperance    seroit  -+=+...+  -^ ,    et   par    consequent 

I'enjeu   de  Pierre  a  celui  de  Paul,  comme 

11  1  .  -      1       1  1 

— 1 —  4-         -I —  a,   I 

8     7  2  8      7     "*     2* 

Si  Paul  parioit  d'amener  juste  dans  les  deux  premiers  coups  seule- 

1       1 
ment,  son  esperance  seroit  o  +  ^  >    et  le   rapport  des  enjeux  celui  de 

1111 
g  +  ^  a  i-g-7. 

S'il  parioit  d'amener  juste  dans  deux  coups   quelconques,  son  espe- 

.^11  11  11 

ranee  seroit  ——+——  +  ...  ^   — ^   —   +  ...  ^    — ^   — ^+... 

8x7      8x6  S  xz     7x6  7x2     6x5 

The  first  question  means,  I  suppose,  that  Paul  undertakes  to  be 
right  once  in  the  seven  cases,  and  wrong  six  times.  His  chance 
then  is 

l/llllllN 

8(,7"^6  +  5  +  4  +  3'^2  +  V- 

For  his  chance  of  being  right  in  the  first  case  and  wrong  in  the 
other  six  is 

16     5      4     8     2      1..       1 

8^r6^.5^4^3^2-''^'^^^^^^^' 


d'alembert.  291 

his  chance  of  being  right  in  the  second  case  and  wrong  in  all  the 

others  is 

7154321,,,.       1 

^X;iX^x-^XjX-Xx,  that  IS 


8     76     5     432'  8x6' 

and  so  on. 

If  the  meaning  be  that  Paul  undertakes  to  be  right  once  at 

7 
least  in  the  seven  cases,  then  his  chance  is  -  .     For  his  chance  of 

o 

being  wrong  every  time  is 

76543211 
8^7^6^5^4^3^2'  ^^  8 ' 

therefore  his  chance  of  being  right  once  at  least  is  1  —  -  ,  that  is  ^  . 

o  8 

Tlie  second  question  means,  I  suppose,  that  Paul  undertakes 
to  be  right  in  the  first  two  cases,  and  wrong  in  the  other  five. 
His  chance  then  is 

1154321,,,.  ■» 

^XsX-X-XtX^Xt;,   that  IS 


8     7     6     5     4      3     2'  8x7x6* 

Or  it  may  mean  that  Paul  undertakes  to  be  right  in  the  first 
two  cases,  but  undertakes  nothing  for  the  other  cases.     Then  his 

.    1      1 

chance  is  ^  x  =■ . 

The  third  question  means,  I  suppose,  that  Paul  undertakes  to 
be  right  in  two  out  of  the  seven  cases  and  wrong  in  the  other  five 
cases.  The  chance  then  will  be  the  sum  of  21  terms,  as  21  combi- 
nations of  pairs  of  things  can  be  made  from  7  things.  The  chance 
that  he  is  right  in  the  first  two  cases  and  wrong  in  all  the  others  is 

1154321,.  1 

gX^x^x^x-x^x^,  that  IS  3  ^  ^  ^  g  ; 

similarly  we  may  find  the  chance  that  he  is  right  in  any  two 
assigned  cases  and  wrong  in  all  the  others.  The  total  chance  will 
be  found  to  be 

8{7(6  +  5-  +  4  +  3  +  2  +  V  +  6(5+4  +  S  +  2  +  V 

19—2 


292  d'alembekt. 

Or  tlie  third  question  may  mean  that  Paul  undertakes  to  be 
right  twice  at  least  in  the  course  of  the  seven  cases,  or  in  other 
words  he  undertakes  to  be  right  twice  and  undertakes  nothing 
more.  His  chance  is  to  be  found  by  subtracting  from  unity  his 
chance  of  being  never  right,  and  also  his  chance  of  being  right  only 
once.     Thus  his  chance  is 


1_1/1      1      1 

8     8  1 7  "^  6  "^  5 


^  +  5+9  +  ...  +  i). 


53-i.  Another  problem  is  given  unconnected  with  the  one  we 
have  noticed,  and  is  solved  correctly. 

The  article  in  the  Encyclopedie  Metliodique  is  signed  with  the 
letter  which  denotes  D'Alembert.  The  date  of  the  volume  is  1784, 
which  is  subsequent  to  D'Alembert's  death ;  but  as  the  work  was 
published  in  parts  this  article  may  have  appeared  during  D'Alem- 
bert's life,  or  the  article  may  have  been  taken  from  his  manu- 
scripts even  if  published  after  his  death.  I  have  not  found  it  in 
the  original  EncycloiJedie :  it  is  certainly  not  under  the  title  Cartes, 
nor  under  any  other  which  a  person  would  naturally  consult.  It 
seems  strange  that  such  errors  should  have  been  admitted  into  the 
Encyclopedie  Methodique. 

Some  time  after  I  read  the  article  Cartes  and  noticed  the 
errors  in  it,  I  found  that  I  had  been  anticipated  by  Binet  in  the 
Comptes  Rendus ...  Vol.  xix.  1844.  Binet  does  not  exhibit  any 
doubts  as  to  the  authorship  of  the  article ;  he  says  that  the  three 
problems  are  wrong  and  gives  the  correct  solution  of  the  first. 

535.  We  will  in  conclusion  briefly  notice  some  remarks  which 
have  been  made  respecting  D'Alembert  by  other  writers. 

536.  Montucla  after  alluding  to  the  article  Croix  ou  Pile  says 
on  his  page  406, 

D'Alembert  ne  s'est  pas  borne  a  cet  exemple,  il  en  a  accumule  plu- 
sieurs  autres,  soit  dans  le  qiiatrieme  volume  de  ses  Opuscules,  1768,  page 
73,  et  page  283  du  cinquieme;  il  s'est  aussi  etaye  dii  suffrage  de  divers 
geometres  qu'il  qiialifie  de  distingues.  Condorcet  a  appuye  ces  objec- 
tions dans  plusieurs  articles  de  rEiicyclopedie  methodique  ou  par  ordre 
de  matieres.      D'un  autre  cote,  divers  autres  geometres  out  entrepris 


d'alembert.  293 

de  r^pondre    aux  raisonnemens   de  d'Alembert,  et  je  crois  qu  en  par- 
ticulier  Daniel  Bernoulli  a  pris  la  defense  de  la  theorie  ordinaire. 

In  this  passage  tlie  word  cinquieme  is  wrong;  it  should  be 
quatrihne.  It  seems  to  me  that  there  is  no  foundation  for  the 
statement  that  Condorcet  supports  D'Alembert's  objections.  Nor 
can  I  find  that  Daniel  Bernoulli  gave  any  defence  of  the  ordinary 
theory ;  he  seems  to  have  confined  himself  to  repelling  the  attack 
made  on  his  memoir  respecting  Inoculation. 

537.  Gouraud  after  referring  to  Daniel  Bernoulli's  controversy 
with  D'Alembert  says,  on  his  page  59, 

...et  quant  au  reste  des  mathematiciens,  ce  ne  fut  que  par  le  silence 
ou  le  dedain  qu'il  r^jDondit  aux  doutes  que  d'Alembert  s'etait  permis 
d'emettre.  Mepris  injuste  et  malhabile  ou  tout  le  monde  avait  a  perdre 
et  qu'une  posterite  moins  prevenue  ne  devait  point  sanctionner. 

The  statement  that  D'Alembert's  objections  were  received  with 
silence  and  disdain,  is  inconsistent  with  the  last  sentence  of  the 
passage  quoted  from  Montucla  in  the  preceding  Article.  According 
to  D'Alembert's  own  words  which  we  have  given  in  Art.  490,  he 
was  attacked  by  some  indifferent  mathematicians. 

538.  Laplace  briefly  replies  to  D'Alembert ;  see  Theorie... des 
Proh.  pages  vii.  and  x. 

It  has  been  suggested  that  D'Alembert  saw  his  error  respecting 
the  game  of  Croix  ou  Pile  before  he  died ;  but  this  suggestion 
does  not  seem  to  be  confirmed  by  our  examination  of  all  his 
■writings :  see  Cambridge  Philosophical  Transactions,  Yol.  ix. 
page  117. 


CHAPTER   XIV. 


BAYES. 


589.  The  name  of  Bayes  is  associated  with  one  of  the  most 
important  parts  of  our  subject,  namely,  the  method  of  estimating 
the  probabihties  of  the  causes  by  which  an  observed  event  may 
have  been  produced.  As  we  shall  see,  Bayes  commenced  the  in- 
vestigation, and  Laplace  developed  it  and  enunciated  the  general 
principle  in  the  form  which  it  has  since  retained. 

540.  We  have  to  notice  two  memoirs  which  bear  the  fol- 
lowing titles : 

An  Essay  towards  solving  a  Prohlem  in  the  Doctrine  of  Chances. 
By  the  late  Rev.  Mr.  Bayes^  F.R.S.  communicated  hy  Mr  Price  in  a 
Letter  to  John  Canton^  A.M.  F.R.S.  A  Demonstration  of  the  Second 
Rule  in  the  Essay  towards  the  Solution  of  a  Prohlem  in  the  Doctrine  of 
Chances,  published  in  the  Philosoi')hical  Transactions,  Vol.  liii.  Com- 
municated hy  the  Rev.  Mr.  Richard  Price,  in  a  Letter  to  Mr.  John 
Canton,  M. A.  F.R.S. 

The  first  of  these  memoirs  occupies  pages  870 — 418  of  Vol.  Liii. 
of  the  Philosophical  Transactions ;  it  is  the  volume  for  1763,  and 
the  date  of  publication  is  1764. 

The  second  memoir  occupies  pages  296 — 825  of  Vol.  Liv.  of  the 
Philosophical  Transactions;  it  is  the  volume  for  1764,  and  the 
date  of  publication  is  1765. 

541.  Bayes  proposes  to  establish  the  following  theorem :  If 


BAYES.  295 

an  event  has  happened  p  times  and  failed  ^  times,  the  probability 
that  its  chance  at  a  single  trial  lies  between  a  and  h  is 


/■ 


x^  (1  -  xy  cix 


i)(f{l-xydx 


Bayes  does  not  use  this  notation  ;  areas  of  curves,  according  to 
the  fashion  of  his  time,  occur  instead  of  integrals.  Moreover  we 
shall  see  that  there  is  an  important  condition  implied  which  we 
have  omitted  in  the  above  enunciation,  for  the  sake  of  brevity: 
we  shall  return  to  this  point  in  Art.  552. 

Bayes  also  gives  rules  for  obtaining  approximate  values  of  the 
areas  which  correspond  to  our  integrals. 

542.  It  will  be  seen  from  the  title  of  the  first  memoir  that  it 
was  published  after  the  death  of  Bayes.  The  Rev.  Mr  Richard 
Price  is  the  well  known  writer,  whose  name  is  famous  in  connexion 
with  politics,  science  and  theology.  He  begins  his  letter  to 
Canton  thus : 

Dear  Sir,  I  now  send  you  an  essay  which  I  have  found  among  the 
papers  of  our  deceased  friend  Mr  Bayes,  and  which,  in  my  opinion,  has 
gi-eat  merit,  and  well  deserves  to  be  preserved. 

543.  The  first  memoir  contains  an  introductory  letter  from 
Price  to  Canton ;  the  essay  by  Bayes  follows,  in  which  he  begins 
with  a  brief  demonstration  of  the  general  laws  of  the  Theory 
of  Probability,  and  then  establishes  his  theorem.  The  enuncia- 
tions are  given  of  two  rules  which  Bayes  proposed  for  finding 
approximate  values  of  the  areas  which  to  him  represented  our 
integrals  ;  the  demonstrations  are  not  given.  Price  himself  added 
An  Appendix  containing  an  Application  of  the  foregoing  Rides 
to  some  particular  Cases. 

The  second  memoir  contains  Bayes's  demonstration  of  his  prin- 
cipal rule  for  approximation  ;  and  some  investigations  by  Price 
which  also  relate  to  the  subject  of  approximation. 

544.  Bayes  begins,  as  we  have  said,  with  a  brief  demonstra- 
tion of  the  general  laws  of  the  Theory  of  Probability ;  this  part  of 
his  essay  is  excessively  obscure,  and  contrasts  most  unfavourably 
with  the  treatment  of  the  same  subject  by  De  Moivre. 


296  BATES. 

Bayes  gives  the  principle  by  which  we  must  calculate  the 
probability  of  a  compound  event. 

Suppose  we  denote  the  probability  of  the  compound  event  by 

p 

-^y  the  probability  of  the  first  event  by  z,  and  the  probability 

of  the  second  on  the  supposition  of  the  happening  of  the  first 

7  P  h 

by  -^ .     Then  our  principle  gives  us  ^^T  =  ^  '^Jf>  ^^^  therefore 

p 

z  =  — .     This  result  Bayes  seems  to  present  as  something  new 

0 

and  remarkable ;  he  arrives  at  it  by  a  strange  process,  and  enun- 
ciates it  as  his  Proposition  5  in  these  obscure  terms : 

If  there  be  two  subsequent  events,  the  probability  of  the   2nd   -^ 

P  .         . 

and  the  probability  of  both  together  -^,  and  it   being    1st   discovered 

that  the  2nd  event  has  happened,  from  hence  I  guess  that  the  1st  event 

.         .     P 
has  also  happened,  the  probability  I  am  in  the  right  is  -r-. 

Price  himself  gives  a  note  which  shews  a  clearer  appreciation 
of  the  proposition  than  Bayes  had. 

b^o.     We  pass  on  now  to  the  remarkable  part  of  the  essay. 

Imagine  a  rectangular  billiard  table  ABCD.    Let  a  ball  be  rolled  on 

it  at  random,  and  when  the  ball  comes  to  rest  let  its  perpendicular 

distance  from  A  She  measured ;  denote  this  by  x.    Let  a  denote  the 

distance  between  AB  and    CD.     Then  the  probability  that  the 

.    c  —  h 

value  of  X  lies  between  two  assio^ned  values  J  and  c  is .     This 

a 

we  should  assume  as  obvious ;  Bayes,  however,  demonstrates  it 

very  elaborately. 

54<6.  Suppose  that  a  ball  is  rolled  in  the  manner  just  ex- 
plained ;  through  the  point  at  which  it  comes  to  rest  let  a  line  EF 
be  drawn  parallel  to  AB,  so  that  the  billiard  table  is  divided  into 
the  two  portions  AEFB  and  EDCF.  A  second  ball  is  to  be  rolled 
on  the  table ;  required  the  probability  that  it  will  rest  within  the 


BATES.  297 

space  AEFB.     If  x  denote  the  distance  between  AB  and  ^i^tlie 


X 


required  probability  is  - :  this  follows  from  the  preceding  Article. 

547.  Bayes  now  considers  the  following  compound  event : 
The  first  ball  is  to  be  rolled  once,  and  so  EF  determined ;  then 
p  +q^  trials  are  to  be  made  in  succession  with  the  second  ball : 
required  the  probability,  before  the  first  ball  is  rolled,  that  the 
distance  of  EF  from  AB  will  lie  between  h  and  c,  and  that  the 
second  ball  will  rest  p  times  within  the  space  AEFB,  and  q  times 
without  that  space. 

We  should  proceed  thus  in  the  solution  :    The  chance  that  EF 

falls  at  a  distance  x  from  AB  is  —  ;  the  chance  that  the  second 

a 

event  then  happens  p  times  and  fails  q^  times  is 

hence  the  chance  of  the  occurrence  of  the  two  contino^encies  is 


a    \p_\q_  \«/    \       «/  * 
Therefore  the  whole  probability  required  is 


a\p[q 


(i-I)''^- 


Bayes's  method  of  solution  is  of  course  very  different  from  the 
above.  With  him  an  area  takes  the  place  of  the  integral,  and 
he  establishes  the  result  by  a  rigorous  demonstration  of  the  ex 
ahsurdo  kind. 

548.  As  a  corollary  Bayes  gives  the  following:  The  proba- 
bility, before  the  first  ball  is  rolled,  that  EF  will  lie  between  AB 
and  CD,  and  that  the  second  event  will  happen  p  times  and  fail  q 
times,  is  found  by  putting  the  limits  0  and  a  instead  of  h  and  c. 
But  it  is  certain  that  EF  will  lie  between  AB  and  CD.    Hence  we 


298  BATES. 

have  for  the  probability,  before  the  first  ball  is  thrown,  that  the 
second  event  will  happen^  times  and  fail  ^  times 


a 


P    <1 


C©'('-3' 


Cv«X/» 


549.  We  now  arrive  at  the  most  important  point  of  the  essay. 
Suppose  we  only  know  that  the  second  event  has  happened  p  times 
and  failed  q  times,  and  that  we  wish  to  infer  from  this  fact  the 
probable  position  of  the  line  ^i^"  which  is  to  us  unknown.  The 
probability  that  the  distance  of  EF  from  AB  lies  between  h 
and  c  is 

I   x'^  {a  —  xy  dx 
•h 

ra 

x^(a-xydx 

J  0 

This  depends  on  Bayes's  Proposition  5,  which  we  have  given 
in  our  Art.  544.  For  let  z  denote  the  required  probability ; 
then 

z  X  probability  of  second  event  =  probability  of  compound  event. 

The  probability  of  the  compound  event  is  given  in  Art.  547, 
and  the  probability  of  the  second  event  in  Art.  548  j  hence  the 
value  of  z  follows. 

550.  Bayes  then  proceeds  to  find  the  area  of  a  certain  curve, 
or  as  we  should  say  to  integrate  a  certain  expression.     We  have 


/ 


^i>+i       ^    ^P^       q{q-l)    x'^' 


X     I  jL    ^  X)    CLX  —~  —  —  ^  ~I~ 


p  +  1      1  J9+  2  '      1.2      ^  +  3      "• 

This  series  may  be  put  in  another  form ;  let  u  stand  for  1  —  x, 
then  the  series  is  equivalent  to 

jj  +  l'^p+l     p  +  2    '^  (p  +  1)  {p-^2)    p  +  S 

q(q-l)(q-2)  x^^r' 

{p  +  l){p-\-'2){p  +  '6)    iJ  +  4    ■^••• 

This  may  be  verified  by  putting  for  u  its  value  and  rearranging 
according  to  powers  of  x.     Or  if  we  differentiate  the  series  with 


BAYES.  299 

respect  to  x^  we  shall  find  that  the  terms  cancel  so  as  to  leave 
only  ^u^, 

551.  The  general  theory  of  the  estimation  of  the  probabilities 
of  causes  from  observed  events  was  first  given  by  Laplace  in  the 
Memoires  ...par  divers  8avans,  Vol.  vi.  1774.  One  of  Laplace's 
results  is  that  if  an  event  has  happened  p  times  and  failed  q 
times,  the  probability  that  it  will  happen  at  the  next  trial  is 


J   0 


x''^'  (1  -  xY  dx 


f 

J   0 


x''  (1  -  xY  dx 


Lubbock  and  Drinkwater  think  that  Bayes,  or  perhaps  rather 
Price,  confounded  the  probability  given  by  Bayes's  theorem  with 
the  probability  given  by  the  result  just  taken  from  Laplace  ;  see 
Lubbock  and  Drinkwater,  page  48.  But  it  appears  to  me  that 
Price  understood  correctly  what  Bayes's  theorem  really  expressed. 
Price's  first  example  is  that  in  which  p  =  1,  and  ^  =  0.  Price  says 
that  "there  would  be  odds  of  three  to  one  for  somewhat  more 
than  an  even  chance  that  it  would  happen  on  a  second  trial." 
His  demonstration  is  then  given  ;  it  amounts  to  this  : 


/: 


af{l-xYdx     .^ 


I  x^Q.-  xy  dx 

J    0 


i' 


8 

where  p  =  l  and  q  =  0.     Thus  there  is  a  probability  -  that  the 

chance  of  the  event  lies  between  ^  and  1,  that  is  a  probability 

3 

7  that  the  event  is  more  likely  to  happen  than  not. 

552.  It  must  be  observed  with  respect  to  the  result  in  Art.  549, 
that  in  Bayes's  own  problem  we  hnonj  that  a  priori  any  position 
of  ^jF  between  AB  and  CD  is  equally  likely  ;  or  at  least  we  know 
what  amount  of  assumption  is  involved  in  this  supposition.  In 
the  applications  which  have  been  made  of  Bayes's  theorem,  and 
of  such  results  as   that  which   we  have  taken   from   Laplace  in 


300  BAYES. 

Art.  551,  there  has  however  often  been  no  adequate  ground  for 
such  knowledge  or  assumption. 

553.  We  have  already  stated  that  Bayes  gave  two  rules  for 
approximating  to  the  value  of  the  area  which  corresponds  to  the 
integral.  In  the  first  memoir,  Price  suppressed  the  demonstrations 
to  save  room  ;  in  the  second  memoir,  Bayes's  demonstration  of  the 
principal  rule  is  given :  Price  himself  also  continues  the  subject. 
These  investigations  are  very  laborious,  especially  Price's. 

The  following  are  among  the  most  definite  results  which  Price 
gives.     Let  n  =p  +  q,  and  suppose  that  neither  p  nor  q  is  small ; 

let  h  =  — //IN  •     Then  if  an  event  has  happened  p  times  and 

failed  q  times,   the   odds  are  about   1   to   1  that  its  chance  at 

a  single  trial  lies  between  -  +  -7^  and 7^  ;  the  odds  are  about 

2  to  1  that  its  chance  at  a  single  trial  lies  between  -  ■\-  h  and 

n 

-^  —  h'.    the  odds   are   about  5  to  1  that   its   chance  at  a  sinsfle 
n  ° 

trial  lies  between  ^  +  A  V2  and  ^  —  h  J%     These  results  may  be 

n  n  "^ 

verified  by  Laplace's  method  of  approximating  to  the  value  of  the 

definite  integrals  on  which  they  depend. 

554.  We  may  observe  that  the  curve  y  —  x^  (1—  xy  has  two 
points  of  inflexion,  the  ordinates  of  which  are  equidistant  from  the 
maximum  ordinate ;  the  distance  is  equal  to  the  quantity  h  of  the 
preceding  Article.  These  points  of  inflexion  are  of  importance  in 
the  methods  of  Bayes  and  Price. 


CHAPTER   XV. 


LAGRANGE. 

555.  Lagrange  was  born  at  Turin  in  1736,  and  died  at 
Paris  in  1813.  His  contributions  to  our  subject  will  be  found  to 
satisfy  the  expectations  which  would  be  formed  from  his  great 
name  in  mathematics. 

556.  His  first  memoir,  relating  to  the  Theory  of  Probability, 
is  entitled  Memoire  sur  VutiliU  de  la  methode  de  prendr^e  le  milieic 
entre  les  resultats  de  plusieurs  observations ;  dans  lequel  on  examine 
les  avantages  de  cette  methode  par  le  calcul  des  prohahilites ;  et  ou 
Von  resoud  differens  prohlenies  relatifs  a  cette  matiere. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  fifth  volume  of  the  Miscellanea 
Taurinensia,  which  is  for  the  years  1770 — 1773  :  the  date  of 
publication  is  not  given.  The  memoir  occupies  pages  167 — 232 
of  the  mathematical  portion  of  the  volume. 

The  memoir  at  the  time  of  its  appearance  must  have  been 
extremely  valuable  and  interesting,  as  being  devoted  to  a  most 
important  subject ;  and  even  now  it  may  be  read  with  ad- 
vantasfe. 


"O" 


557.  The  memoir  is  divided  into  the  discussion  of  ten  pro- 
blems ;  by  a  mistake  no  problem  is  numbered  9,  so  that  the  last 
two  are  10  and  11. 

The  first  problem  is  as  follows :  it  is  supposed  that  at  every 
observation  there  are  a  cases  in  which  no  error  is  made,  h  cases 
in  which  an  error  equal  to  1  is  made,  and  h  cases  in  which  an 


302  LAGEANGE. 

error  equal  to  —  1  is  made ;  it  is  required  to  find  the  probability 
that  in  taking  the  mean  of  n  observations,  the  result  shall  be 
exact. 

In  the  expansion  of  {«  +  5  (ic  +  cc~^)}"  according  to  powers  of  x, 
find  the  coefficient  of  the  term  independent  of  x\  divide  this 
coefficient  by  {a  +  2^)"  which  is  the  whole  number  of  cases  that 
can  occur  ;  we  thus  obtain  the  required  probability. 

Lagrange  exhibits  his  usual  skill  in  the  management  of  the 
algebraical  expansions.  It  is  found  that  the  probability  diminishes 
as  n  increases. 

558.  We  may  notice  two  points  of  interest  in  the  course  of 
Lagrange's  discussion  of  this  problem.  Lagrange  arrives  indirectly 
at  the  following  relation 

„      [n  (n  —  1)1  ^      {n(n  —  1)  (n  — 


2.3  J"^*" 


^  1.3.5...  (2n~l)       , 
1.2.3...71 


and  he  says  it  is  the  more  remarkable  because  it  does  not  seem 
easy  to  demonstrate  it  a  i^riori. 

The  result  is  easily  obtained  by  equating  the  coefficients  of  the 
term  independent  of  x  in  the  equivalent  expressions 


(1  +  ^rfl  +  iy,  and^li^ 


^2n 
XI    '  X'' 


This  simple  method  seems  to  have  escaped  Lagrange's  notice. 

Suppose  we  expand  ■  in  powers  of  z ;   let  the 

V 1  —  2as  —  cz^ 

result  be  denoted  by 

1  +  A^z  +  A/  +  A/  -f  ... ; 

Lagrange  gives  as  a  known  result  a  simple  relation  which  exists 
between  every  three  consecutive  coefficients ;  namely 

.   _2n  —  l       .  n  —  1     J 


LAGEAXGE.  303 

This  may  be  established  by  differentiation.     For  thus 

that  is 

(a+cz)  {l-{-A^z  +  A,/  +  ..,  +Ay+  ...} 

=  (l-2a2-cs')  [Aj^  +  2A^z  +  .,,  +nA^z''~'-^  ...}; 
then  by  equating  coefficients  the  result  follows. 

559.  In  the  second  problem  the  same  suppositions  are  made 
as  in  the  first,  and  it  is  required  to  find  the  probability  that  the 

error  of  the  mean  of  n  observations  shall  not  surpass  +  —  . 

Like  the  first  problem  this  leads  to  interesting  algebraical  ex- 
pansions. 

We  may  notice  here  a  result  which  is  obtained.  Suppose  we 
expand  {a  +  5  (ic +  £c"^)}"  in  powers  of  x\  let  the  result  be  de- 
noted by 

A^  +  A^  (x-^x-')  +A^  {x'^x-')  -{-A,  {x'+x-^  +  ...  ; 

Lagrange  wishes  to  shew  the  law  of  connexion  between  the  co- 
efficients Aq,  A^,  A^, ...  This  he  effects  by  taking  the  logarithms 
of  both  sides  of  the  identity  and  differentiating  with  respect  to  x. 
It  may  be  found  more  easily  b}"  putting  2  cos  ^  for  a?  +  x~^,  and 
therefore  2  cos  rO  for  a?*"  +  x~'\     Thus  we  have 

(a  +  25  cos  ey  =  ^0  +  ^A  cos  6  +  2A^  cos  26  +  2A^  cos  8^  +  . . . 

Hence,  by  taking  logarithms  and  differentiating, 

Tib  sin  6     _  A^  sin  6  +  2A^  sin  26  +  ^A^  sin  3^  +. . . 
a-^2bco^6~     A^  +  2A^ cos 6  +  2A^ cos  2^  +  . . . 

Multiply  up,  and  arrange  each  side  according  to  sines  of  mul- 
tiples of  6  \  then  equate  the  coefficients  of  sin  r6 :  thus 

rib  [A,_^  -  A,^,]  =  raA,  +  b  [{r  -  1)  A,_^  -f  (r  +  1)  A,^,] ; 
therefore  A^^,  =  b  {n-r^rl)  A     -raA^ 


30i  LAGEANGE. 

560.  In  the  third  problem  it  is  supposed  that  there  are  a 
cases  at  each  observation  in  which  no  error  is  made,  h  cases  in 
which  an  error  equal  to  —  1  is  made,  and  c  cases  in  which  an  error 
equal  to  r  is  made  ;  the  probability  is  required  that  the  error  of 
the  mean  of  n  observations  shall  be  contained  within  given 
limits. 

In  the  fourth  problem  the  suppositions  are  the  same  as  in  the 
third  problem ;  and  it  is  required  to  find  the  most  probable  error 
in  the  mean  of  n  observations ;  this  is  a  particular  case  of  the 
fifth  problem. 

561.  In  the  fifth  problem  it  is  supposed  that  every  observation 
is  subject  to  given  errors  which  can  each  occur  in  a  given  number 
of  cases  ;  thus  let  the  errors  be  p,  q^  r,  s,  ...  ^  and  the  numbers  of 
cases  in  which  they  can  occur  be  a,  h,  Cyd,  ...  respectively.  Then 
we  require  to  find  the  most  probable  error  in  the  mean  of  n  ob- 
servations. 

In  the  expansion  of  {ax^  +  hx^  +  cic**  +  ...)"  let  M  be  the  coeffi- 
cient of  iC* ;  then  the  probability  that  the  sum  of  the  errors  is  yit, 

and  therefore  that  the  error  in  the  mean  is  —  is 

n 

M 

Hence  we  have  to  find  the  value  of  //.  for  which  M  is  greatest. 

Suppose  that  the  error  p  occurs  a  times,  the  error  q  occurs 
/3  times,  the  error  r  occurs  7  times,  and  so  on.     Then 

a  +  /3  +  7+ =n, 

pOL  +  ql3  +  ry -\- =  fi. 

It  appears  from  common  Algebra  that  the  greatest  value  of  fjL 

is  when 

a_/3_7_  _  n 

a      h      c      a4-&  +  c+..'' 

^T    ,  Lb     pa-^-  qh  +  rc-\- ... 

so  that  -  —^ S • 

n         a  +  6  +  c+  ... 

This  therefore  is  the  most  probable  error  in  the  mean  result. 

562.  With  the  notation  of  Art.  561,  suppose  that  a,  h,  c,  ... 


LAGRANGE.  305 

are  not  known  d  priori;  but  that  ct,  /S,  y,  ...  are  known  by  ob- 
servation. Then  in  the  sixth  problem  it  is  taken  as  evident  that 
the  most  probable  values  of  a,  h,  c,  ...  are  to  be  determined  from 
the  results  of  observation  by  the  relations 

a  =  ;8  =  7"--" 
so  that  the  value  of  -  of  the  jjreceding  Article  may  be  written 

fM  _pa.  +  ql3  +ry+  ... 
n         a  +  /3  +  7+... 

Lagrange  proposes  further  to  estimate  the  probability  that  the 
values  of  a,  h,  c,  ...  thus  determined  from  observation  do  not  differ 
from  the  true  values  by  more  than  assigned  quantities.  This  is  an 
investigation  of  a  different  character  from  the  others  in  the 
memoir;  it  belongs  to  what  is  usually  called  the  theory  of  in- 
verse probability,  and  is  a  difficult  problem. 

Lagrange  finds  the  analytical  difficulties  too  great  to  be  over- 
come ;  and  he  is  obliged  to  be  content  with  a  rude  approxi- 
mation. 

563.  The  seventh  problem  is  as  follows.  In  an  observation  it 
is  equally  probable  that  the  error  should  be  any  one  of  the 
following  quantities  —a,  -  (a  -  1),  ...  —  1,  0,  1,  2  ...  13  ;  required 
the  probability  that  the  error  of  the  mean  of  n  observations  shall 
have  an  assigned  value,  and  also  the  probability  that  it  shall  lie 
between  assigned  limits. 

We  need  not  delay  on  this  problem  ;  it  really  is  coincident 
with  that  in  De  Moivre  as  continued  by  Thomas  Simpson :  see 
Arts.  14^8  and  S64<.  It  leads  to  algebraical  work  of  the  same  kind 
as  the  eighth  problem  which  we  will  now  notice. 

oQ4^.  Suppose  that  at  each  observation  the  error  must  be 
one  of  the  following  quantities  —  &,  -  (a  —  1),  ...  0,  1,  ...  a ;  and 
that  the  chances  of  these  errors  are  proportional  respectively  to 
1,  2,  ...  a  + 1,  a,  ...  2,  1  :  required  the  probability  that  the  error  in 

Lb 

the  mean  of  n  observations  shall  be  equal  to  -  . 

20 


SOG  LAGRANGE. 

We  must  find  the  coefficient  of  x>^  in  the  expansion  of 

{^-«  +  2a?-"+^  +  ...  +  aa?-'  +  (a  +  1)  x°  +  ao;  +  .. .  +  2a;"-'  +  a;"}", 

and  divide  it  by  the  vahie  of  this  expression  when  aj  =  1,  which  is 
the  whole  number  of  cases  ;  thus  we  obtain  the  required  pro- 
babiHty. 

Now      1+  2x  +  3a;'+  ...  +  (a+  1)  a;"+  ...  +  2a;""-'  +  x^ 


Jia 


a+i\  2 


=  {iJ,x+x'-\-...  +  xy=(Kj^^  . 

Hence  finally  the  required  probability  is  the  coefficient  of 
a;'*  in  the  expansion  of 

1         a;-""  (1  -  a;"-^y"  ^ 
that  is  the  coefficient  of  a;'^"^""  in  the  expansion  of 

^,(i-.r(i-o- 

Lagrange  gives  a  general  theorem  for  effecting  expansions,  of 
which  this  becomes  an  example ;  but  it  will  be  sufficient  for  our 
purpose  to  employ  the  Binomial  Theorem.  We  thus  obtain  for 
the  coefficient  of  a?'^"^""  the  expression 


+ \    ^     ^  </)(7ia+At  +  l-2«-2) 

%i  {271  - 1)  {2n  -  2)  ^  ,  .      o        ON         1 
12    3 "  0(wa+/^  +  l-3a-S)4-...|; 

where  0  (r)  stands  for  the  product 

r  (r+1)  (r  +  2)  . . .  (r  +  2w  -  2)  ; 

the  series  within  the  brackets  is  to  continue  only  so  long  as  r  is 
positive  in  (j)  (r). 

565.  We  can  see  a  priori  that  the  coefficient  of  xf^  is  equal 
to  the  coefficient  of  x~'^,  and  therefore  when  we  want  the  former 
we  may  if  we  please  find  the  latter  instead.     Thus  in  the  result  of 


LAGRANGE.  "  307 

Art.  564>,  we  may  if  we  please  put  —  //,  instead  of  /jl,  without 
changing  the  vakie  obtained.  It  is  obvious  that  this  would  be 
a  gain  in  practical  examples  as  it  would  diminish  the  number 
of  terms  to  be  calculated. 

This  remark  is  not  given  by  Lagrange. 

566.  We  can  now  find  the  probability  that  the  error  in  the 
mean  result  shall  lie  between  assigned  limits.  Let  us  find  the 
probability  that  the  error  in  the  mean  result  shall  lie  between 

and  -  ,  both  inclusive.    We  have  then  to  substitute  in  the 

n  n 

expression  of  Article  56^  for  //,  in  succes.sion  the  numbers 

—  ny,    —(iia  —  l),    ...7  — 1,    7, 

and  add  the  results.  Thus  we  shall  find  that,  usingf  ^,  as  is 
customary,  to  denote  a  summation,  we  have 

S^  (7ia  +  /^  +  1)  =  — -^/r  (7ia  +  7  +  1), 

where  -^/r  (?-)  stands  for 

r  (r  +  1)  (?'  +  2)  . . .  (r  +  %i  -  1). 

When  we  proceed  to  sum  <^  (?ia  +  //-  —  ct)  we  must  remember 
that  we  have  only  to  include  the  terms  for  which  noL  +  fi  —  a  is 
positive;  thus  we  find 

Xcj)  (na  +  fJ' —  OL)  =  ~  yjr  {iiOL  4-  7  -  a). 
Proceeding  in  this  way  we  find  that  the  probability  that  the 

710L  "V 

error-  in  the  mean  result  will  lie  between and  - ,   both  in- 

n  n 

elusive,   is 

r^r-  J-v/r  (nOL  +  7  +  1)  —  2/1  -v/r  (nct.  +  7  +  1— a—  1) 

+       \    ^ — '  -^  (71a  +  7  +  1  -  2a  -  2) 

2w  i^n  -  1)  (2?i  -  2)    ,   ,       ,       ,  .       „        ^s   .       \ 
^     ^    ./  ^^ ^  ^  {no,  +  7  +  1  -  3a  -  3)  +  . .  .|  ; 

20—2 


308  LAGRANGE. 

the  series  tuithin  the  brackets  is  to  continue  only  so  long  as  r  is 
positive  in  yjr  (r).      We  will  denote  this  by  F^y). 

The  probability  that  the  mean  error  will  lie  between  /3  and  y, 
where  7  is  greater  than  /3,  is  F[y)  —  F  {^)  if  we  include  7  and 
exclude  ^  ;  it  is  F{y  —  1)  —  F{/3  —  1)  if  we  exclude  7  and  include 
/9;  it  is  F{y)—F[(3—1)  if  we  include  both  7  and  yS ;  it  is 
F{y  —  1)  —F{/3)  if  we  exclude  both  7  and  /3. 

It  is  the  last  of  these  four  results  which  Lagrange  gives. 

We  have  deviated  slightly  from  his  method  in  this  Article  in 
order  to  obtain  the  result  with  more  clearness.  Our  result  is 
F  {y  —  1)  —  F  {^) ;  and  the  number  of  terms  in  F  (y-l)  is  de- 
termined by  the  law  that  r  in  ^fr  (r)  is  always  to  be  positive  : 
the  number  of  terms  in  F  ((3)  is  to  be  determined  in  a  similar 
manner,  so  that  the  number  of  terms  in  F  (/3)  is  not  necessarily 
so  great  as  the  number  of  terms  in  F  (y  —  l).  Lagrange  gives  an 
incorrect  law  on  this  point.  He  determines  the  number  of  terms 
in  F{y  —  1)  correctly;  and  then  he  j^'^ohngs  F {,6)  until  it  has 
as  many  terms  as  F{y  —  1)  by  adding  fictitious  terms. 

567.  Let  us  now  modify  the  suppositions  at  the  beginning 
of  Art.  564^.  Suj^pose  that  instead  of  the  errors  —  a,  —  (a  —  l),  ... 
we  are  liable  to  the  errors  —  ka,  —  k  {a  —  l),  ...  Then  the  investi- 
gation in  Art.  5Q4!  gives  the  probability  that  the  error  in  the  mean 

ak 
result  shall  be   equal  to  —  ;  and  the  investigation  in  Art.  5G6 

gives  the  probability  that  the  error  in  the  mean  result  shall  lie 

between  —  and  -    .     Let  a  increase  indefinitely  and  k  diminish 
71  n 

indefinitely,  and  let  o.k  remain  finite  and  equal  to  h.     Let  7  and  /3 

also  increase  indefinitely ;  and  let  7  =  c«  and  I3  =  h(x  where  c  and  h 

are  finite.     We  find  in  the  limit  that  F  [y]  —  F  {/S)  becomes 

J-  L  +  ny''-2n  (c  +  n-ir^  +  ^"^  ^^"^  ~  ^^  (c  +  n-  2^-  .. 


each  series  is  to   continue  only  so  long  as  the  quantities  which 
are  raised  to  the  power  2n  are  positive. 


LAGRANGE.  309 

This  result  expresses  the  probability   that   the   error  in  the 

mean  result  will   lie   between    —  and  —    on   the  followinof  hy- 

n  n  o     J 

pothesis  ;  at  every  trial  the  error  may  have  any  value  between 
—  h  and  +  h ;  positive  and  negative  errors  are  equally  likely ; 
the  probability  of  a  positive  error  z  is  proportional  to  h  —  z,  and 

in  fact  ~ — — -  is  the  probability  that  the  error  will  lie  be- 
tween z  and  z  +  Sz. 

We  have  followed  Lagrange's  guidance,  and  our  result  agrees 
with  his,  except  that  he  takes  7i  =  l,  and  his  formula  involves 
many  misprints  or  errors. 

568.  The  conclusion  in  the  preceding  Article  is  striking.  We 
have  an  exact  expression  for  the  probability  that  the  error  in 
the  mean  result  will  lie  between  assigned  limits,  on  a  very  7^ea- 
sonahle  hypothesis  as  to  the  occiirrence  of  single  errors. 

Suppose  that  positive  errors  are  denoted  by  abscissse  measured 
to  the  right  of  a  fixed  point,  and  negative  errors  by  abscissae 
measured  to  the  left  of  that  fixed  point.  Let  ordinates  be  drawn 
representing  the  probabilities  of  the  errors  denoted  by  the  re- 
spective abscissae.  The  curve  which  can  thus  be  formed  is  called 
the  curve  of  errors  by  Lagrange ;  and  as  he  observes,  the  curve 
becomes  an  isosceles  triangle  in  the  case  which  we  have  just 
discussed. 

569.  The  matter  which  we  have  noticed  in  Arts.  563,  dQ>^, 
566,  567,  568,  had  all  been  published  by  Thomas  Simpson,  in  his 
Miscellaneous  Tracts,  1757 ;  he  gave  als(3  some  numerical  illus- 
trations :  see  Art.  371. 

570.  The  remainder  of  Lagrange's  memoir  is  very  curious ; 
it  is  devoted  to  the  solution  and  exemplification  of  one  general 
problem.  In  Art.  567  we  have  obtained  a  result  for  a  case  in 
which  the  error  at  a  single  trial  may  have  any  value  between 
fixed  limits  ;  but  this  result  was  not  obtained  directly :  we  started 
with  the  supposition  that  the  error  at  a  single  trial  must  be  one 
of  a  certain  specified  number  of  errors.  In  other  words  we  started 
with  the  hypothesis  of  errors  changing  per  saltum  and  passed  on 


o 


10  LAGKANGE. 


to  the  supposition  of  continuous  errors.  Lagrange  wishes  to  solve 
questions  relative  to  continuous  errors  without  starting  with  the 
supposition  of  errors  changing  per  saltum. 

Suppose  that  at  every  observation  the  error  must  lie  between  h 
and  c;  let  ^  {x)  dx  denote  the  probabiUty  that  the  error  will  lie 
between  x  and  x-\-dx\  required  the  probability  that  in  n  obser- 
vations the  sum  of  the  errors  will  lie  between  assigned  limits  say 
/3  and  7.  Now  what  Lagrange  effects  is  the  following.  He  trans- 
forms   \\   ^{pc)a^dx\    into    \f{z)(idz,  where  f{z)   is   a  known 

function  of  z  which  does  not  involve  a,  and  the  limits  of  the 
integral  are  known.  When  we  say  that  f  {£)  and  the  limits  of 
z  are  known  we  mean  that  they  are  determined  from  the  known 
function  ^  and  the  known  limits  h  and  c.  Lagrange  then  says 
that  the  probability  that  the  sum  of  the  errors  will  lie  between 

/?  and  7  is  1   f{z)  dz.     He  apparently  concludes  that  his  readers 

will  admit  this  at  once  ;  he  certainly  does  not  demonstrate  it. 
We  will  indicate  presently  the  method  in  which  it  seems  the  de- 
monstration must  be  put. 

571.  After  this  general  statement  we  will  give  Lagrange's 
first  example. 

Suppose  that  ^  {x)  is  constant  =  K  say  ;  then 

6  (x)  «*  dx  =  — i^ , 

J  h  loof  a 


b\n 


therefore  \j    (b(x)a'dx[   = — —^ — r-f— 

Vb^'  j  (log  a)" 

Now  we  may  suppose  that  a  is  greater  than  unity,  and  then  it 
may  be  easily  shewn  that 


J  0 


n-l 


(log  ay' 

thus  \      (f){x)  a^  dx\   =  -^  {a'  -  a^  j    if ''a'"  dy. 


LAGRANGE.  311 

Let  c-'h  =  t,  and  expand  {a'  —  a^y  by  the  Binomial  Theorem  ; 
thus  '         W    (fi  {x)  a"  dx\ 


b 


^j— yja    -na      +      2. 2  ~***l/    ^     «^     «^- 


Now  decompose    I    ^"  ^oP'dy  into  its  elements;  and  multiply 

0 
them  by  the  series  within  brackets.     AVe  obtain  for  the  coefficient 

of  a^'^  the  expression 


where  the  series  within  brackets  is  to  continue  only  so  long  as  the 
quantities  raised  to  the  power  n  —  1  are  positive. 

Let  nc—y  =  z  ;  then  dy  —  —  dz\  when  y—^  we  have  z  =  nc, 
and  when  y  =  00  we  have  0  =  —  00  .  Substitute  nc  —  z  for  ?/,  and 
we  obtain  finally 


where  f{z)  = \  [nc  —  zy  ^  -  n  {nc  -  z  -ty 


+     \,2    '  {nc-z-2ty'-.. 

the  series  within  brackets  being  continued  only  so  long  as  the 
quantities  raised  to  the  power  n  —  1  are  positive. 

Lagrange  then  says  that  the  probability  that  the  sum  of  the 
errors  in  n  observations  will  lie  between  /3  and  7  is 

f  V(.)  dz. 

J/3 

572.  The  result  is  correct,  for  it  can  be  obtained  in  another 
way.  We  have  only  to  carry  on  the  investigation  of  the  problem 
enunciated  in  Art.  563  in  the  same  way  as  the  problem  enunciated 
in  Art.  564  was  treated  in  Art.  567;  the  result  will  be  very  similar 
to  those  in  Art.  567.  Lagrange  thus  shews  that  his  process  is 
verified  in  this  example. 


312  LAGRANGE. 

573.  In  the  problem  of  Art.  570  it  is  obvious  that  the  sum 
of  the  errors  must  lie  between  nb  and  nc.  Hence  f[z)  ought 
to  vanish  if  z  does  not  lie  between  these  limits;  and  we  can 
easily  shew  that  it  does. 

For  if  z  be  greater  than  7ic  there  is  no  term  at  all  in  f{z), 
for  every  quantity  raised  to  the  power  n  —  1  would  be  negative. 

And  if  z  be  less  than  nh,  then  f{z)-  vanishes  by  virtue  of  the 
theorem  in  Finite  Differences  which  shews  that  the  n^^  difference 
of  an  algebraical  function  of  the  degree  n—1  is  zero. 

This  remark  is  not  given  by  Lagrange. 

574.  We  will  now  supply  what  we  presume  would  be  the 
demonstration  that  Lagrange  must  have  had  in  view. 

Take  the  general  problem  as  enunciated  in  Art.  570.  It  is 
not  difficult  to  see  that  the  following  process  v/ould  be  suitable 
for  our  purpose.  Let  a  be  any  quantity,  which  for  convenience 
we  may  suppose  greater  than  unity.  Find  the  value  of  the  ex- 
pression 

\  i(f)  {xj  a^i  dxjr  \  Icj)  {x^)  a^2  dxA J  j</)  {x^)  a^»  dxA  , 

where  the  integrations  are  to  be  taken  under  the  following 
limitations ;  each  variable  is  to  lie  between  b  and  c,  and  the  sum 
of  the  variables  between  z  and  z  +  Bz.      Put  the  result  in  the 

form  Pa^Sz  ;  then   I    Pdz  is  the  required  probability. 

J/3 

Now  to  find  P  we  proceed  in  an  indirect  way.  It  follows  from 
our  method  that 

'ne 


(f>  {x)  d"  dx\   =i     Pddz. 

J  b  )  J  lib 


But  Lagrange  by  a  suitable  transformation  shews  that 

'    (f>  {x)  d'dxi   =  I  ^f{z)  a'dz, 

h  )  J  Zo 

where  z^  and  ^^  are  known.     Hence 

rnc  fz 

Pa'dz=       f[z)a'dz. 

J  nb  J  Xo  ' 

It  will  be  remembered  that  a  may   be    ani/  quantity   which 


LAGRANGE.  813 

is  greater  than  unity.     We  shall  shew  that  we  must  then  have 

Suppose  that  z^  is  less  than  nh^  and  z^  greater  than  nc.     Then 
we  have 

1    f{z)a'dz+       {f{z)-F}  a'dz'-\-       f{z)a'dz  =  ^, 

J  SSq  J  nb  '1  nc 

for  all  values  of  a.  Decompose  each  integTal  into  elements ;  put 
a^^  =  p.  We  have  then  idtimately  a  result  of  the  following 
form 


a- 


^0    jr,   +     T^p   +    V  +    ^3P'+    -    ^^^   ^V-    •••}    =   0, 


where  T^,  T^,...  are  independent  of  p.  And  p  may  have  any 
positive  value  we  please.  Hence  by  the  ordinary  method  of  in- 
determinate coefficients  we  conclude  that 

Thus  P=f{^)- 

The  demonstration  will  remain  the  same  whatever  supposition 
be  made  as  to  the  order  of  magnitude  of  the  limits  z^  and  z^ 
compared  with  nh  and  7ic. 

57o.  Lagrange  takes  for  another  example  that  which  we  have 
akeady  discussed  in  Art.  567,  and  he  thus  again  verifies  his 
new  method  by  its  agreement  with  the  former. 

He  then  takes  two  new  examples ;  in  one  he  supposes  that 

<f)  {x)  =  K  \/ c^  —  x\  the  errors  lying  between  —  c  and  c;  in  the 
other  he  supposes  that  cj)  (x)  =  Kcosoo,  the  errors  lying  between 

-  :=:   and  ^  . 
2  2 

576.  We  have  now  to  notice  another  memoir  by  Lagrange 
which  is  entitled  Becherches  sw  les  suites  reciirrentes  dont  les 
termes  varient  de  plusieurs  manieres  di0rentes,  qu  sur  Vintegra- 
tion  des  equations  lineaires  aux  differences  jinies  et  partielles ;  et 
sur  Tusage  de  ces  equations  dans  la  theorie  des  hazards. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  Nouveaux  Menioires  de  VAcad. 
...  Berlin.     The   volume  is  for  the  year  1775;  the  date  of  pub- 


314  LAGRANGE. 

lication  is  1777.     The  memoir  occupies  pages  183 — 272 ;  the  ap- 
l^lication  to  the  Theory  of  Chances  occupies  pages  240 — 272. 

577.  The  memoir  begins  thus  ; 

J'ai  clonne  dans  le  premier  Volume  des  Memoires  de  la  Societe  des 
Sciences  de  Turin  une  metliode  nouvelle  pour  traiter  la  theorie  des  suites 
recurrentes,  en  la  faisant  dependre  de  Tintegration  des  equations  lineaires 
aux  differences  finies.  Je  me  proposois  alors  de  pousser  ces  recherches 
l>lus  loin  et  de  les  appliquer  principalement  a  la  solution  de  plusieurs 
problemes  de  la  theorie  des  liasards;  mais  d'autres  objets  m'ayant  depuis 
fait  perdre  celui  la  de  vue,  M.  de  la  Place  m'a  prevenu  en  grand  partie 
dans  deux  excellens  Memoires  sur  les  suites  recurro-recurrentes,  et  sur 
V  integration  des  equations  differentielles  finies  et  leur  iisage  dans  la 
theorie  des  liasards^  imprimes  dans  les  Volumes  vi  et  vii  des  Memoires 
pr^sentes  a  1' Academic  des  Sciences  de  Paris.  Je  crois  cependant  qu'on 
peut  encore  aj  outer  quelque  chose  au  travail  de  cet  illustre  Geometre,  et 
traiter  le  meme  sujet  d'une  maniere  plus  directe,  plus  simple  et  surtout 
plus  generale ;  c'est  I'objet  des  Recherches  que  je  vais  donner  dans  ce 
Memoire;  on  y  trouvera  des  methodes  nou veil es  pour  I'integration  des 
equations  lineaires  aux  differences  finies  et  partielles,  et  I'application  de 
ces  methodes  a  plusieurs  problenies  interessans  du  calcul  des  probabilites ; 
mais  il  n'est  question  ici  que  des  equations  dont  les  coefficiens  sont  con- 
stants, et  je  reserve  pour  un  autre  Memoire  I'examen  de  celles  qui  ont 
des  coefficiens  variables. 

578.  We  shall  not  delay  on  the  part  which  relates  to  the 
Integration  of  Equations  ;  the  methods  are  simple  but  not  so  good 
as  that  of  Generating  Functions.  We  proceed  to  the  part  of  the 
memoir  which  relates  to  Chances. 

579.  The  first  problem  is  to  find  tlie  chance  of  the  happening 
of  an  event  h  times  at  least  in  a  trials. 

Let  j9  denote  the  chance  of  its  happening  in  one  trial ;  let 
?/^^^  denote  the  probability  of  its  happening  t  times  in  x  trials ; 
then  Lagrange  puts  down  the  equation 

He  integrates  and  determines  the  arbitrary  quantities  and  thus 
arrives  at  the  usual  result. 

In  a  Corollary  he  applies  the  same  method  to  determine  the 


LAGRANGE.  31o 


chance  that  the  event  shall  happen  just  h  times  ;  he  starts  from 
the  same  equation  and  by  a  different  determination  of  the  arbi- 
trary quantities  arrives  at  the  result  which  is  well  known, 
namely, 

y  (1  -pr'  \a_ 


\b  \a  —  h 


Lagrange  refers  to  De  Moivre,  page  15,  for  one  solution,  and 
adds :  mais  celle  que  nous  venons  d'en  donner  est  non  seulement 
plus  simple,  mais  elle  a  de  plus  I'avantage  d'etre  d^duite  de  prin- 
cipes  directs. 

But  it  should  be  observed  that  De  Moivre  solves  the  problem 
again  on  his  page  27;  and  here  he  indicates  the  modern  method, 
which  is  self-evident.     See  Art.  257. 

It  seems  curious  for  Lagrange  to  speak  of  his  method  as  more 
simple  than  De  Moivre's,  seeing  it  involves  an  elaborate  solution 
of  an  equation  in  Finite  Differences. 

580.  Lagrange's  second  problem  is  the  following : 

On  sujDpose  qu'a  chaqiie  coup  il  puisse  arriver  deux  6venemens  dont 
les  probabilites  respectives  soient  p  et  q;  et  on  demande  le  sort  d'un 
joueur  qui  parieroit  d'amener  le  premier  de  ces  evenemens  h  fois  au 
moins  et  le  second  c  fois  au  moins,  en  un  nombre  a  de  coups. 

The  enunciation  does  not  state  distinctly  what  the  suppositions 
really  are,  namely  that  at  every  trial  either  the  first  event  happens, 
or  the  second,  or  neither  of  them ;  these  three  cases  are  mutually 
exclusive,  so  that  the  probability  of  the  last  at  a  single  trial 
is  1  —p  —  q.  It  is  a  good  problem,  well  solved ;  the  solution  is 
presented  in  a  more  elementary  shape  by  Trembley  in  a  memoir 
which  we  shall  hereafter  notice. 

581.  The  third  problem  is  the  following  : 

Les  memes  choses  etant  supposees  que  daus  le  Probleme  li,  on  de- 
mande le  sort  d'un  joueur  qui  parieroit  d'amener,  dans  un  nombre  de 
coups  indetermine,  le  second  des  deux  Evenemens  h  fois  avant  que  le 
premier  fut  arrive  a  fois. 

Let  7/^ J  be  the  chance  of  the  player  when  he  has  to  obtain  the 
second  event  t  times  before  the  first  event  occurs  x  times.     Then 


316  LAGl^ANGE. 

This  leads  to 


yx,t  -  q  |i  +  f/?  +  — 2 — P  + 273 '  ^ 


+  ... 


(5  +  ic-  2 


^  -  1  1  .-r  -  1 


This  result  agrees  with  the  second  formula  in  Art.  172. 

582.  The  fourth  problem  is  like  the  third,  only  three  events 
may  now  occur  of  which  the  probabilities  are  p,  q,  r  respectively. 
In  a  Corollary  the  method  is  extended  to  four  events;  and  in 
a  second  Corollary  to  any  number. 

To  this  problem  Lagrange  annexes  the  following  remark  : 
Le  Probleme  dont  nous  venons  de  donner  une  solution  tres  generale 
et  tres  simple  renferme  d'luie  maniere  generale  celui  qu'on  nomme  com- 
munement  dans  I'analyse  des  liasards   le   probleme   des  partis,   et  qui 
n'a  encore  ete  resolu  complettement  que  pour  le  cas  de  deux  joueurs. 

He  then  refers  to  Montmort,  to  De  Moivre's  second  edition, 
Problem  VI,  and  to  the  memoir  of  Laplace. 

It  is  very  curious  that  Lagrange  here  refers  to  De  Moivre's 
second  edition,  while  elsewhere  in  the  memoir  he  always  refers  to 
the  third  edition ;  for  at  the  end  of  Problem  vi.  in  the  third 
edition  De  Moivre  does  give  the  general  rule  for  any  number  of 
players.  This  he  first  published  in  his  Miscellanea  Analytica, 
page  210  ;  and  he  reproduced  it  in  his  Doctrine  of  Chances.  But 
in  the  second  edition  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances  the  rule  was  not 
given  in  its  natural  place  as  part  of  Problem  vi.  but  appeared  as 
Problem  LXix. 

There  is  however  some  difference  between  the  solutions  given 
by  De  Moivre  and  by  Lagrange ;  the  difference  is  the  same  as 
that  which  we  have  noticed  in  Art.  175  for  the  case  of  two  players. 
De  Moivre's  solution  resembles  the  first  of  those  which  are  given 
in  Art.  172,  and  Lagrange's  resembles  the  second. 

It  is  stated  by  Montucla,  page  397,  that  Lagrange  intended 
to  translate  De  Moivre's  third  edition  into  French. 

583.  Lagrange's  fifth  problem  relates  to  the  Duration  of  Play, 
in  the  case  in  which  one  player  has  unlimited  capital ;  this  is  De 
Moivre's  Problem  LXV:  see  Art.  307.  Lagrange  gives  three  solu- 
tions.     Lagrange's   first   solution   demonstrates   the  result   given 


LAGRANGE.  31 


Ht 


without  demonstration  in  De  Moivres  second  solution ;  see 
Art.  309.  We  will  give  Lagrange's  solution  as  a  specimen  of  his 
methods.  We  may  remark  that  Laplace  had  preceded  Lagrange 
in  the  discussion  of  the  problem  of  the  Duration  of  Play.  La- 
place's investigations  had  been  published  in  the  Memoires  . . .  par 
Divers  Savans,  Vols.  vi.  and  Yii. 

Laplace  did  not  formally  make  the  supposition  that  one  player 
had  unlimited  capital,  but  we  arrive  at  this  case  by  supposing 
that  his  symbol  i  denotes  an  infinite  number ;  and  we  shall  thus 
find  that  on  page  158  of  Laplace's  memoir  in  Vol.  vii.  of  the 
Memoires... par  Divers  Savans,  we  have  in  effect  a  demonstration 
of  De  Moivre's  result. 

We  proceed  to  Lagrange's  demonstration. 

584.  The  probability  of  a  certain  event  in  a  single  trial  is^  ; 
a  player  bets  that  in  a  trials  this  event  will  happen  at  least 
h  times  oftener  than  it  fails  :  determine  the  player's  chance. 

Let  y^i  represent  his  chance  when  he  has  x  more  trials  to 
make,  and  when  to  ensure  his  success  the  event  must  happen  at 
least  t  times  oftener  than  it  fails.  Then  it  is  obvious  that  we  re- 
quire the  value  of  7/„^j^. 

Suppose  one  more  trial  made  ;  it  is  easy  to  obtain  the  follow- 
ing equation 

The  player  gains  when  ^  =  0  and  x  has  any  value,  and  he  loses 
when  x=0  and  t  has  any  value  greater  than  zero ;  so  that  y^^^=\ 
for  any  value  of  x,  and  y^^t^  0  for  any  value  of  t  gTeater 
than  0. 

Put  ^  for  1  —p,  then  the  equation  becomes 

To  integrate  this  assume  y  =  ^a'^/3* ;  we  thus  obtain 

p  -  a/B  +  q/3'  =  0. 

From  this  we  may  by  Lagrange's  Theorem  expand  /S'  in  powers 
of  a ;  there  will  be  two  series  because  the  quadratic  equation 
gives  two  values  of  /S  for  an  assigned  value  of  a.  These  two 
series  are 


318  LAGRANGE. 


^~a''^   0.'^'   ^     1.2       a'^'    '^         1.2.3  ^^^^   +••• 


0.^      fpo!-'     t{t-Z)  p'o!-'      t{t-^)  (t-5)  for" 
i       i~^  1.2       2'"'  1-2.3  2'"' 

If  then  we  put  in  succession  these  values  of  /3*  in  the  ex- 
pression Ao^  ^^  we  obtain  two  series  in  powers  of  a,  namely, 

Af  |a^-  +  ipq^^'-'  +  ^-^^  //a--^  +  . . .  J  , 

and  Aq-'  \o^'  -  tjpqa''^'-'  +  *-^j^  fi^'^'"  -  .  • 

Either  of  these  series  then  would  be  a  solution  of  the  equation 
in  Finite  Differences,  whatever  may  he  the  values  of  A  and  a ; 
so  that  we  should  also  obtain  a  solution  by  the  sum  of  any  number 
of  such  series  with  various  values  of  A  and  a. 

Hence  we  infer  that  the  general  solution  will  be 

y.,  =  p'  {/ {^-t)  +  tpqfix -t-2)+  ^^t^pYfix - < - 4) 

+  ^^T4^i'W(— 6)  +  ...} 
+  q-'  U,  ix  +  t)-  tfq  ,^  (a;  +  «  -  2)  +  '-^^ pY  <l>{x+t-i) 

Here  f  [x)  and  <^  {x)  represent  functions,  at  present  arbitrary, 
which  must  be  determined  by  aid  of  the  known  particular  values 
of  Vx,^  and  ?/„,,. 

Lagrange  says  it  is  easy  to  convince  ourselves,  that  the  con- 
dition 2/^^=0  when  t  has  any  value  greater  than  0  leads  to  the 
following  results  :  all  the  functions  with  the  characteristic  0  must 
be  zero,  and  those  with  the  characteristic  /  must  be  zero  for  all 
negative  values  of  the  quantity  involved.  [Perhaps  this  will  not 
appear  very  satisfactory ;  it  may  be  observed  that  q~*'  will  become 
indefinitely  great  with  t,  and  this  suggests  that  the  series  whicli 
multiplies  q~^  should  be  zero.] 

Thus  the  value  of  y^^t  becomes  a  series  with  a  finite  number 
of  terms,  namely, 


LAGRANGE.  819 

y...  =P'  {/(^  -t)  +  tpqfix  -  <  -  2)  +  '-^J^^Y/(^  -  <  -  4) 

the  series  extends  to  ^  (a?  —  ^  +  2)  terms,  or  to  ^  (a?  -  ^  +  1)  terms, 

according  as  ic  —  ^  is  even  or  odd. 

The  other  condition  is  that  j/a;,o—  ^y  ^''^^  ^^7  vakie  of  x.  But  if 
we  put  ^  =  0  we  have  yx,Q=f{p^)'  Hence  f{x)  =  l  for  every 
positive  value  of  x.     Thus  we  obtain 

the  series  is  to  extend  to  3  (x  —  t  +  2)  terms,  or  to  ^  (x  —  t-\-l) 

terms.     This  coincides  with  the  result  in  De  Moivre's  second  form 
of  solution :  see  Art.  309. 

585.  Lagrange  gives  two  other  solutions  of  the  problem  just 
considered,  one  of  which  presents  the  result  in  the  same  form  as 
De  Moivre's  first  solution.  These  other  two  solutions  by  Lagi^ange 
differ  in  the  mode  of  integrating  the  equation  of  Finite  Differences  ; 
but  they  need  not  be  further  examined. 

586.  Lagrange  then  proceeds  to  the  general  problem  of  the 
Duration  of  Play,  supposing  the  players  to  start  with  different 
capitals.  He  gives  two  solutions,  one  similar  to  that  in  De 
Moivre's  Problem  LXiii,  and  the  other  similar  to  that  in  De 
Moivre's  Problem  Lxviii.  The  second  solution  is  very  remarkable ; 
it  demonstrates  the  results  which  De  Moivre  enunciated  without 
demonstration,  and  it  puts  them  in  a  more  general  form,  as  De 
Moivi'e  limited  himself  to  the  case  of  equal  capitals. 

587.  Lagrange's  last  problem  coincides  with  that  given  by 
Daniel  Bernoulli  which  we  have  noticed  in  Art.  417.  Lagrange 
supposes  that  there  are  n  urns ;  and  in  a  Corollary  he  gives  some 
modifications  of  the  problem. 

588.  Lagrange's  memoir  would  not  now  present  any  novelty 
to  a  student,  or  any  advantage  to  one  who  is  in  possession  of  the 
method  of  Generating  Functions.    But  nevertheless  it  may  be  read 


820  LAGRANGE. 

with  ease  and  interest,  and  at  the  time  of  pubhcation  its  value 
must  have  been  great.  The  promise  held  out  in  the  introduction 
that  something  would  be  added  to  the  labours  of  Laplace  is 
abundantly  fulfilled.  The  solution  of  the  general  problem  of  the 
Duration  of  Play  is  conspicuously  superior  to  that  which  Laplace 
had  given,  and  in  fact  Laplace  embodied  some  of  it  subsequently 
in  his  own  work.  The  important  pages  231 — 233  of  the  Theorie 
. . .  des  Proh.  are  substantially  due  to  this  memoir  of  Lagrange's. 

589.  We  may  notice  a  memoir  by  Lagrange  entitled  Me- 
moire  sur  une  question  concernant  les  annuiies. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  volume  of  the  Memoires  de 
V Acad. ...  Berlin  for  1792  and  1793;  the  date  of  publication  is 
1798  ;  the  memoir  occupies  pages  235 — 246. 

The  memoir  had  been  read  to  the  Academy  ten  years  before. 

590.  The  question  discussed  is  the  following:  A  father  wishes 
to  pay  a  certain  sum  annually  during  the  joint  continuance  of  his 
own  life  and  the  minority  of  all  his  children,  so  as  to  ensure  an 
annuity  to  his  children  after  his  death  to  last  until  all  have  attained 
their  majority. 

Lagrange  denotes  by  A,  B,  G, ...  the  value  of  an  annuity  of 
one  crown  for  the  minority  of  the  children  A,  B,  G ...  respectively. 
Then  by  AB  he  denotes  the  value  of  an  annuity  of  one  crown 
for  the  joint  minority  of  two  children  A  and  B ;  and  so  on.  Hence 
he  obtains  for  the  value  of  an  annuity  payable  as  long  as  either 
^  or  ^  is  a  minor, 

~A  +  B-  AB. 

Lagrange  demonstrates  this ;  but  the  notation  renders  it  almost 
obviously  self  evident. 

Similarly  the  value  of  an  annuity  payable  as  long  as  one  of 
three  children  A,  B,  G  remains  a  minor  is 


A  +  B  +  C  -  AB  -  AG  -  BG  +  ABG. 

De  Moivre  however  had  given  this  result  in  his  Treatise  of 
Annuities  on  Lives,  and  had  used  the  same  notation  for  an  annuity 
on  joint  lives. 

Lagrange  adds  two  tables  which  he  calculated  from  his 
formulae,  using  the  table  of  mortality  given  in  the  work  of 
Sussmilch. 


CHAPTER  XVI. 

MISCELLANEOUS    INVESTIGATIONS 

Between  the  Years  1750  and  1780. 


591.  The  present  Chapter  will  contain  notices  of  various  con- 
tributions to  our  subject  which  were  made  between  the  years  1750 
and  1780. 

592.  We  first  advert  to  a  work  bearing  the  following  title : 
Piece  qui  a  remport^  le  prix  sur  le  sujet  des  Evenemens  Fortuits, 
propose  par  VAcademie  Roy  ale  des  Sciences  et  Belles  Lettres  de 
Berlhi  pour  Vann^e  1751.    Avec  les  p)ieces  qui  ont  concouru. 

This  work  is  a  quarto  volume  of  238  pages ;  we  notice  it 
because  the  title  might  suggest  a  connexion  with  our  subject, 
which  we  shall  find  does  not  exist. 

The  Academy  of  Berlin  proposed  the  following  subject  for  dis- 
cussion : 

Les  Evenemens  heureux  et  malheurenx,  ou  ce  que  nous  apj)elIons 
Bonheur  et  Malheur  dependant  de  la  volonte  ou  de  la  permission  de 
Dieu,  de  sorte  que  le  terme  de  fortune  est  un  nom  sans  realite;  on  de- 
mande  si  ces  Evenemens  nous  obligent  a  de  certains  devoirs,  quels  sont 
ces  devoirs  et  quelle  est  leur  etendue. 

The  prize  was  awarded  to  Kaestner  professor  of  Mathematics  at 
Leipsic ;  the  volume  contains  his  dissertation  and  those  of  his 
competitors. 

There  are  nine  dissertations  on  the  whole ;  the  prize  disserta- 
tion is  given  both  in  French  and  Latin,  and  the  others  in  French 

21 


322  DODSON.      HOYLE. 

or  German  or  Latin.  The  subject  was  perhaps  unpromising  ;  the 
dissertations  are  not  remarkable  for  novelty  or  interest.  One  of 
the  best  of  the  writers  finishes  with  a  modest  avowal  which  might 
have  been  used  by  all : 

Ich  maclie  hier  den  Schluss,  weil  ich  ohnehin  mit  gar  zii  guten 
Griinden  fiirchte,  zu  weitliiufig  gewesen  zu  seyn,  da  ich  so  wenig  neues 
artiges  und  scharfsinniges  gesagt  habe.  Ich  finde  auch  in  dieser  Probe, 
dass  mein  Wille  noch  einmahl  so  gut  als  meine  iibrige  Tahigkeit,  ist. 

593.  A  work  entitled  the  Mathematical  Repository,  in  three 
volumes,  was  published  by  James  Dodson,  Accomptant  and  Teacher 
of  the  Mathematics.  The  work  consists  of  the  solution  of  Mathe- 
matical problems.  The  second  volume  is  dated  1753 ;  pages 
82 — 136  are  occupied  with  problems  on  chances :  they  present 
nothing  that  is  new  or  important.  The  remainder  of  this  volume 
is  devoted  to  annuities  and  kindred  subjects ;  and  so  also  is  the 
Avhole  of  the  third  volume,  which  is  dated  1755. 

594.  Some  works  on  Games  of  Chance  are  ascribed  to  Hoyle 
in  Watt's  Bihliotheca  Britannica.  I  have  seen  only  one  of  them 
which  is  entitled:  An  Essay  towards  making  the  Doctrine  of 
Chances  easy  to  those  who  understand  Vidgar  Arithmetick  only: 
to  which  is  added,  some  useful  tables  on  annuities  for  lives  (&c.  &c.  &c. 
By  Mr  Hoyle...  It  is  not  dated;  but  the  date  1754  is  given  in 
"Watt's  Bihliotheca  Britannica. 

The  work  is  in  small  octavo  size,  with  large  tjrpe.  The  title, 
preface,  and  dedication  occupy  viii  pages,  and  the  text  itself  occu- 
pies 73  pages.  Pages  1 — 62  contain  rules,  without  demonstration, 
for  calculating  chances  in  certain  games  ;  and  the  remainder  is  de- 
voted to  tables  of  annuities,  and  to  Halley's  Breslau  table  of  life, 
with  a  brief  explanation  of  the  latter.     I  have  not  tested  the  rules. 

595.  We  advert  in  the  next  place  to  a  work  which  is  en- 
titled DelV  Azione  del  Caso  nelle  Invenzioni,  e  deW  influsso  degli 
Astri  ne  Corpi  Terrestri  Dissertazioni  due. 

This  is  a  quarto  volume  of  220  pages,  published  anonymously 
at  Padua,  1757.  It  is  not  connected  with  the  Theory  of  Pro- 
bability ;    we  notice  it  because  the  title  might  perhaps  suggest 


SAMUEL   CLARK.  323 

such  connexion,  especiallysvLen  abbreviated,  as  in  the  Catalogues 
of  Booksellers. 

The  first  dissertation  is  on  the  influence  of  chance  in  inven- 
tions, and  the  second  on  the  influence  of  the  celestial  bodies  on 
men,  animals,  and  plants.  The  first  dissertation  recognises  the 
influence  of  chance  in  inventions,  and  gives  various  examples  ;  the 
second  dissertation  is  intended  to  shew  that  there  is  no  influence 
produced  by  the  celestial  bodies  on  men,  animals,  or  plants,  in  the 
sense  in  which  astrologers  understood  such  influence. 

The  author  seems  to  have  been  of  a  sanguine  temperament ; 
for  he  obviously  had  hopes  that  the  squaring  of  the  circle  would 
be  eventually  obtained ;  see  his  pages  31,  40,  85. 

On  the  other  hand  his  confidence  is  not  great  in  the  Newtonian 
theory  of  gravitation ;  he  thinks  it  may  one  day  follow  its  prede- 
cessor, the  theory  of  vortices,  into  oblivion ;  see  his  pages  45,  172. 

The  following  is  one  of  his  arguments  against  Lunar  influence. 
If  there  be  such  influence  we  must  conceive  it  to  arise  from  exhala- 
tions from  the  Moon,  and  if  the  matter  of  these  exhalations  be 
supposed  of  appreciable  density  it  will  obstruct  the  motions  of  the 
planets,  so  that  it  will  be  necessary  from  time  to  time  to  clean  up 
the  celestial  paths,  just  as  the  streets  of  London  and  Paris  are 
cleaned  from  dust  and  dirt.     See  his  page  164. 

The  author  is  not  very  accurate  in  his  statements.  Take  the 
following  specimen  from  his  page  74 :  Jacopo  III.  Re  d'Inghilterra 
alia  vista  d'una  spada  ignuda,  come  riferisce  il  Cavaliere  d'Igby, 
sempre  era  compreso  d'un  freddo,  e  ferale  spavento.  This  of 
course  refers  to  James  I.  Again  ;  we  have  on  his  page  81 :  ...ci5 
che  disse  in  lode  d'Aristotile  il  Berni :  II  gran  Maestro  de  color 
die  sanno.  It  is  not  often  that  an  Italian  ascribes  to  any  inferior 
name  the  honour  due  to  Dante. 

596.  We  have  next  to  notice  a  work  by  Samuel  Clark  en- 
titled TheLaius  of  Chance  :  or,  a  Mathematical  Investigation  of  the 
Prohabilities  arising  from  amj  proposed  Circumstance  of  Play. 
London,  1758. 

This  is  in  octavo  ;  there  is  a  Preface  of  2  pages,  and  204 
pages  of  text.  The  book  may  be  described  as  a  treatise  based  on 
those  of  De  Moivre  and   Simpson;    the  abstruse   problems    are 

21—2 


324  SAMUEL   CLARK. 

omitted,  and  many  examples  and  illustrations  are  given  in  order 
to  render  the  subject  accessible  to  persons  not  very  far  advanced 
in  mathematics. 

The  book  presents  nothing  that  is  new  and  important.  The 
game  of  bowls  seems  to  have  been  a  favourite  with  Clark ;  he 
devotes  his  pages  44 — 68  to  problems  connected  with  this  game. 
He  discusses  at  great  length  the  problem  of  finding  the  chance  of 
throwing  an  assigned  number  of  points  with  a  given  number  of 
similar  dice;  see  his  pages  113 — ISO.  He  follows  Simpson,  but 
he  also  indicates  De  Moivre's  Method ;  see  Art.  364.  Clark 
begins  the  discussion  thus  : 

In  order  to  facilitate  the  solution  of  this  and  the  following  problem, 
I  shall  lay  down  a  lemma  which  was  communicated  to  me  by  my  inge- 
nious friend  Mr  William  Fayne,  teacher  of  mathematics. 

The  Le7tima. 

The  sum  of  1,  3,  6,  10,  15,  21,  28,  36,  &c.  continued  to  (n)  number 

J,  ^  .  ,  ^    n  +  2      n  +  1      n 

01  terms  is  equal  to  — ^ —  x  — ^—  x  -  . 

It  was  quite  unnecessary  to  appeal  to  William  Pa3riie  for  such 
a  well-known  result ;  and  in  fact  Clark  himself  had  given  on  his 
page  84  Newton's  general  theorem  for  the  summation  of  series ; 
see  Art.  152. 

Clark  discusses  in  his  pages  139 — 153  the  problem  respecting 
a  run  of  events,  which  we  have  noticed  in  Art.  325.  Clark  detects 
the  slight  mistake  which  occurs  in  De  Moivre's  solution ;  and  from 
the  elaborate  manner  in  which  he  notices  the  mistake  we  may 
conclude  that  it  gave  him  great  trouble. 

Clark  is  not  so  fortunate  in  another  case  in  which  he  ventures 
to  differ  with  De  Moivre  ;  Clark  discusses  De  Moivre's  Problem  ix. 
and  arrives  at  a  different  result ;  see  Art.  269.  The  error  is 
Clark's.  Taking  De  Moivre's  notation  Clark  assumes  that  A  must 
either  receive  q  G  from  B,  or  pay  jiL  to  B.  This  is  wrong.  Sup- 
pose that  on  the  whole  A  wins  in  5'  -F  m  trials  and  loses  in  m  trials  ; 
then  there  is  the  required  difference  of  q  games  in  his  favour.  In 
this  case  he  receives  from  B  the  sum  {(i  + 111)  G  and  pays  to  him 
the  sum  m.L  ;  thus  the  balance  is  qG  +  m  {G  —  L)  and  not  qG  SiS 
Clark  says. 


IklALLET.      JOHN   BERNOULLI.  325 

597.  We  have  next  to  notice  a  memoir  by  Mallet,  entitled 
Recherches  sur  les  avantages  de  trots  Joueurs  qui  font  entreux  une 
Poule  au  trictrac  ou  a  un  autre  Jeu  quelconque. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  Acta  Helvetica... Basilece, 
Vol.  V.  1762  ;  the  memoir  occupies  pages  230 — 248.  The  problem 
is  that  of  De  Moivre  and  Waldegrave ;  see  Art.  211.  Mallet's 
solution  resembles  that  given  byDe  Moivre  in  his  pages  132 — 138. 

Mallet  however  makes  some  additions.  In  the  problem  as  treated 
by  De  Moivre  the  fine  exacted  from  each  defeated  player  is  con- 
stant; Mallet  considers  the  cases  in  which  the  fines  increase  in 
arithmetical  progression,  or  in  geometrical  progression.  A  student 
of  De  Moivre  will  see  that  the  extensions  given  by  Mallet  can  be 
treated  without  any  difficulty  by  De  Moivre's  process,  as  the  series 
which  are  obtained  may  be  summed  by  well-known  methods. 

598.  The  same  volume  which  contains  Euler's  memoir  which 
we  have  noticed  in  Art.  438,  contains  also  two  memoirs  by  Beguelin 
on  the  same  problem.  Before  we  notice  them  it  will  be  convenient 
to  consider  a  memoir  by  John  Bernoulli,  which  in  fact  precedes 
Beguelin's  in  date  of  composition  but  not  in  date  of  publication. 
This  John  Bernoulli  was  grandson  of  the  John  whom  we  named 
in  Art.  194.  John  Bernoulli's  memoir  is  entitled  Sur  les  suites  ou 
sequences  dans  la  loterie  de  Genes.  It  was  published  in  the  volume 
for  1769  of  the  Histoii^e  de  VAcad Berlin;  the  date  of  pub- 
lication is  1771  :  the  memoir  occupies  pages  234 — 253.  The  fol- 
lowing note  is  given  at  the  beginning  : 

Ce  Memoire  a  ete  In  en  1765,  apres  le  Memoire  de  Mr.  Euler  sur 
cette  matiere  insere  dans  les  Memoires  de  I'Academie  pour  cette  annee. 
Comme  les  Memoires  de  Mr.  Beguelin  imprimes  a  la  suite  de  celui  de 
Mr.  Euler  se  rapportent  au  mien  en  plusieurs  endroits,  et  que  la  Loterie 
qui  I'a  occasione  est  phis  en  vogue  que  jamais,  je  ne  le  supprimerai  pas 
plus  longtems.  Si  ma  methode  ne  mene  pas  aussi  loin  que  celle  de 
Mrs.  Euler  et  Beguelin,  elle  a  du  moins,  je  crois,  I'avantage  d'etre  plus 
facile  a  saisir. 

599.  In  the  first  paragraph  of  the  memoir  speaking  of  the 
question  respecting  sequences,  John  Bernoulli  says  : 

Je  m'en  occupai  done  de  terns  en  tems  jusqu'a  ce  que  j'appris  de 
Mr.   Euler  qu'il  traitoit  le  meme  sujet;  e'en  fiit  assez  pour  me  faire 


326  JOHN    BERNOULLI. 

abandonner  mon  dessein,  et  je  me  reservai  seulement  de  voir  par  le 
Memoire  de  cet  illustre  Geometre  si  j'avois  raisonue  juste;  il  a  eu  la 
bonte  de  me  le  commuDiquer  et  j'ai  vu  que  le  peu  que  j'avois  fait,  etoit 
fonde  sur  des  raisonnemens  qui,  s'ils  n'etoient  pas  sublimes,  n'etoient  du 
moins  pas  faux. 

600.  Jobn  Bernoulli  does  not  give  an  Algebraical  investiga- 
tion ;  lie  confines  himself  to  the  arithmetical  calculation  of  the 
chances  of  the  various  kinds  of  sequences  that  can  occur  when 
there  are  90  tickets  and  2  or  3  or  4  or  5  are  drawn.  His  method 
does  not  seem  to  possess  the  advantage  of  facility,  as  compared 
with  those  of  Euler  and  Beguelin,  which  he  himself  ascribes  to  it. 

601.  There  is  one  point  of  difference  between  John  Bernoulli 
and  Euler.  John  Bernoulli  supposes  the  numbers  from  1  to  90 
ranged  as  it  were  in  a  circle  ;  and  thus  he  counts  90,  1  as  a 
binary  sequence  ;  Euler  does  not  count  it  as  a  sequence.  So  also 
John  Bernoulli  counts  89,  90,  1  as  a  ternary  sequence ;  with  Euler 
this  would  count  as  a  binary  sequence.     And  so  on. 

It  might  perhaps  have  been  anticipated  that  from  the  greater 
symmetry  of  John  Bernoulli's  conception  of  a  sequence,  the  in- 
vestigations respecting  sequences  would  be  more  simple  than  on 
Euler's  conception ;  but  the  reverse  seems  to  be  the  case  on  ex- 
amination. 

In  the  example  of  Art.  440  corresponding  to  Euler's  results 

o         /        ON/        ON          (n-2)  (n-S)  {n-4<) 
n-2,        {n  -  2)  (n  -  3),        -^^ ^  ^    ^   g , 

we  shall  find  on  John  Bernoulli's  conception  the  results 

602.  There  is  one  Algebraical  result  given  which  we  may 
notice.  Euler  had  obtained  the  following  as  the  chances  that  there 
would  be  no  sequences  at  all  in  the   case   of  n  tickets ;   if  two 

tickets  be  drawn  the  chance  is  ,  if  three  -^^ ^'-W^ —  ,  if 

n  n{n  —  l) 

four  (^-4)(^-5)(n-6)  (^,5)(.^-6)(^-7)(/^-8)  . 

n{n-\){n-2)       '  "  "^^        n{n-l)  {n-2)  {n-^)        ' 

and  so  the  law  can  be  easily  seen.     Now  John  Bernoulli  states 


JOHN    BERNOULLI.  327 

that  on  his  conception  of  a  sequence  these  formulae  will  hold  if  we 
change  n  into  n  —  1.  He  does  not  demonstrate  this  statement, 
so  that  we  cannot  say  how  he  obtained  it. 

It  may  be  established  by  induction  in  the  following  way.  Let 
^  (n,  r)  denote  the  number  of  ways  in  which  we  can  take  r  tickets 
out  of  n,  free  from  any  sequence,  on  Euler's  conception  of  a  se- 
quence. Let  B  [n,  r)  denote  the  corresponding  number  on  John 
BernoulH's  conception.     Then  we  have  given 

^,      .       (n—r-{-l)(n  —  r)...(n  —  2r-\-2) 
E{n,  r)  =  ^ ^ ^ ^ ^  , 

and  we  have  to  shew  that 

^  ,       .       n(n  —  T  —  1)  ...  (71—  2r  +  1) 
B  in,  r)  =  — ^ '- ^ . 

For  these  must  be  the  values  of  E  (w,  r)  and  B  [n,  r)  in  order 
that  the  appropriate  chances  may  be  obtained,  by  dividing  by  the 
total  number  of  cases.     Now  the  following  relation  will  hold  : 

E{n,r)=B{n,r)  +  B{7i-l,  r -1)  -E{n-2,  r-l). 

The  truth  of  this  relation  will  be  seen  by  taking  an  example. 
Suppose  n  is  10,  and  r  is  3.  Now  every  case  which  occurs  in 
the  total  B  [n,  r)  will  occur  among  the  total  E  {n,  r) ;  but  some 
which  do  not  occur  in  B{n,r)  will  occur  in  E{n,r),  and  these 
must  be  added.     These  cases  which  are  to  be  added  are  such  as 

(10,  1,  3)  (10, 1,  4) (10,  1,  8).  We  must  then  examine  by  what 

general  law  we  can  obtain  these  cases.  We  should  form  all  the 
binary  combinations  of  the  numbers  1 .  2,  ...  9  which  contain  no 
Bernoullian  sequence,  and  which  do  contain  1. 

And  generally  we  should  want  all  the  combinations  r  —  1  at  a 
time  which  can  be  made  from  the  first  n—1  numbers,  so  as  to  con- 
tain no  Bernoullian  sequence,  and  to  contain  1  as  one  of  the  num- 
bers. It  might  at  first  appear  that  B  (n  —  1,  r  —  V)—B(7i—2,  r  — 1) 
would  be  the  number  of  such  combinations ;  but  a  little  con- 
sideration will  shew  that  it  is  B  {n  —  1,  r  —  1)  —  E  {n  —  2,  7*  —  1),  as 
we  have  given  it  above. 

Thus  having  established  the  relation,  and  found  the  value  of 
B  {ti,  1)  independently  we  can  infer  in  succession  the  values  of 
B  (n,  2),  B  {n,  3),  and  so  on. 


328  BEGUELIN. 

603.  We  now  consider  Beguelin's  two  memoirs.  These  as  we 
have  stated  are  contained  in  the  same  volume  as  Euler's  memoir 
noticed  in  Art.  438.  The  memoirs  are  entitled  Bur  les  suites  ou 
sequences  dans  la  lotterie  de  Genes ;  they  occupy  pages  231 — 280 
of  the  volume. 

604.  Beguelin's  memoirs  contain  general  Algebraical  formulae 
coinciding  with  Euler's,  and  also  similar  formulae  for  the  results  on 
John  Bernoulli's  conception;  thus  the  latter  formulae  constitute 
what  is  new  in  the  memoirs. 

605.  We  can  easily  give  a  notion  of  the  method  which 
Beguelin  uses.  Take  for  example  13  letters  a,  h,  c,  ...  i,j,  h,  l,  m. 
Arrange  5  files  of  such  letters  side  by  side,  thus 


a 

a 

a 

a 

a 

I 

h 

h 

h 

h 

c 

c 

c 

c 

c 

•  •  ■ 

,m    m   m   771    m 

Consider  first  only  two  such  files ;  take  any  letter  in  the  first 
file  and'  associate  it  with  any  letter  in  the  second  file ;  we  thus 
get  13^^  such  associations,  namely  aa,  ah,  ac  ...  ha,  hh,  he,  ... 

Here  we  have  ah  and  ha  both  occurring,  and  so  ac  and  ca,  and 
the  like.  But  suppose  we  wish  to  prevent  such  repetitions,  we  can 
attain  our  end  in  this  way.  Take  any  letter  in  the  first  file  and 
associate  it  with  those  letters  only  in  the  second  file,  which  are  in  the 
same  rank  or  in  a  lower  rank.  Thus  the  a  of  the  first  file  will  be 
associated  with  any  one  of  the  13  letters  of  the  second  file  ;  the  h  of 
the  second  file  will  be  associated  with  any  one  of  the  12  letters 
in  the  second  file  beginning  with  h.     Thus  the  whole  number  of 

13  X  14 

such  associations  will  be  13  +  12  +  .  ..  +  1;  that  is       ..    ^     . 

'  1.2 

Similarly  if  we  take  three  files  we  shall  have  13^  associations 

if  we  allow  repetitions ;  but  if  we  do  not  allow  repetitions  we 

13  X  14  X  15 

shall  have   — ^ — ^— ,     Proceeding  in  this  way  we  find  that  if 

JL  X  ^  X  o 

there  are  five  files  and  we  do  not  allow  repetitions  the  number  of 
13x14x15x16x17 


associations  is 


1x2x3x4x5 


BEGUELIN.  829 

All  this  is  well  known,  as  Beguelin  says,  but  it  is  introduced 
by  him  as  leading  the  way  for  his  further  investigations. 

606.  Such  cases  as  a,  a,  a,  a,  a  cannot  occur  in  the  lottery 
because  no  number  is  there  repeated.  Let  the  second  file  be 
raised  one  letter,  the  third  file  two  letters;  and  so  on.  Thus 
we  have 

a       h       c       d      e 

h       c       d      e       f 


•  •  • 
• 

• 

J 

h 

I       m 

• 

7 

h 

I 

m 

h 

I 

m 

I 

m 

m 


We  have  thus  13  —  4  complete  files,  that  is  9  complete  files  ; 
and,  proceeding  as  before,  the  number  of  associations  is  found  to  be 

9  X  10  X  11  X  12  X  13      ,.       ,  ,       . 

— — ^ — -. z —  ;  that  IS,  the  number  is  what  we  know  to 

1x2x3x4x0 

be  the  number  of  the  combinations  of  13  things  taken  5  at  a  time. 

607.  Suppose  now  that  we  wish  to  find  the  number  of  asso- 
ciations in  which  there  is  no  sequence  at  all.  Raise  each  file  two 
letters  instead  of  one,  so  that  we  now  have 


a 

c 

e 

9 

I 

h 

d 

f 

h 

• 

J 

c 

e 

9 

9 

I 

k 

d 

f 

h 

• 

J 

I 

e 

9 

• 

^ 

k 

m 

i 

h 

• 

3 

I 

9 

• 

^ 

k 

m 

h 

• 

I 

k 
« 

h 

m 

• 

J 

I 

k 

m 

I 

m 

830  BEGUELIN. 

Here  there   are   only   13  —  8,  that  is,   5  complete  files;    and 
proceeding  as  in  Art.  605,  we  find  that  the  whole  number  of  asso- 
5x6x7x8x9 


ciations  IS 


1x2x3x4x5 


In  this  way  we  arrive  in  fact  at  the  value  which  we  quoted 
for  E{7i,  r)  in  Art.  602. 

608.  The  method  which  we  have  here  briefly  exemplified  is 
used  by  Begnelin  in  discussing  all  the  parts  of  the  problem. 
He  does  not  however  employ  letters  as  we  have  done ;  he  supposes 
a  series  of  medals  of  the  Roman  emperors,  and  so  instead  of 
a,  h,  c,...he  uses  Augustus^  Tiberius,  Caligula,  ... 

609.  It  may  be  useful  to  state  the  results  which  are  obtained 
when  there  are  n  tickets  of  which  5  are  drawn. 

In  the  following  table  the  first  column  indicates  the  form,  the 
second  the  number  of  cases  of  that  form  according  to  Euler's 
conception,  and  the  third  the  number  according  to  John  Ber- 
noulli's conception. 

Sequence  of  5,  n  —  4,  n. 

Sequence  of  4,  {n  —  5)  {n  —  4),  n{n  —  Q). 

Sequence   of  3 

combined  with  (n-5)  {n  —  4<),  n{n-6). 

a  sequence  of  2, 

Sequence  of  3, 

and  the  other  (n  —  6)  {n—  o)  [n  —  4)         n  {n  —  7)  {n  —  6) 

numbers  not  1.2  '  1.2 

in  sequence, 

Two  sequences  {n  —  6)  {n—  5)  {n  —  4)         n{n  —  7)  (n  —  6) 

of  2,  1.2  '  172  • 

Single  sequence        {n-7)  (w-6)  (n-5)  (m-4)       n  {n-8)  {n-7)  (w-6) 
of  2,  1.2.3  '  17273  • 

No  sequence,  see  Art.  602. 


BEGUELIN.  331 

The  chance  of  any  assigned  event  is  found  by  dividing  the 
corresponding  number  by  the  whole  number  of  cases,  that  is  by  the 
number  of  combinations  of  n  things  taken  5  at  a  time. 

610.  We  have  now  to  notice  another  memoir  by  Beguehn. 
It  is  entitled,  Sur  V usage  du  principe  de  la  raison  suffisante  dans 
le  calcul  des  jprohabilites. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  volume  of  the  Histoire  de 
V Acad.... Berlin  iox  1767;  the  date  of  publication  is  1769:  the 
memoir  occupies  pages  382 — 412. 

611.  Beguelin  begins  by  saying,  J'ai  montre  dans  un  Memoire 
precedent  que  la  doctrine  des  probabilites  etoit  uniquement  fondee 
sur  le  principe  de  la  raison  suffisante  :  this  refers  apparently  to 
some  remarks  in  the  memoirs  which  we  have  just  examined. 
Beguelin  refers  to  D'Alembert  in  these  words.  Un  illustre  Auteur, 
Geometre  et  Philosophe  a  la  fois,  a  public  depuis  peu  sur  le 
Calcul  des  probabilites,  des  doutes  et  des  questions  bien  dignes 
d'etre  approfondies  ...  Beguelin  proposes  to  try  how  far  meta- 
physical principles  can  assist  in  the  Theory  of  Probabilities. 

612.  Beguelin  discusses  two  questions.  The  first  he  says  is 
the  question : 

...  si  les  evenemens  simmetriques  et  regnliers,  attribues  an  hazard, 
sont  (toutes  choses  d'ailleurs  egales)  aiissi  probables  que  les  evenemens 
qui  n'ont  ni  ordre  ni  regularity,  et  au  cas  qu'ils  aient  le  nieme  degre  de 
probabilite,  d'ou  vient  que  leur  regularite  nous  frappe,  et  qu'ils  nous 
paroissent  si  singuliers  ? 

His  conclusions  on  this  question  do  not  seem  to  call  for  any 
remark. 

613.  His  next  question  he  considers  more  difficult ;  it  is 

. . .  lorsqu'un  meme  evenement  est  deja  arrive  nne  ou  plusieurs  fois 
de  suite,  on  demande  si  cet  evenement  conserve  autant  de  probabilite 
pour  sa  future  existence,  que  Tevenement  contraire  qui  avec  une  egale 
probabilite  primitive  n'est  point  arrive  encore. 

BegTielin  comes  to  the  conclusion  that  the  oftener  an  event 
has  happened  the  less  likely  it  is  to  happen  at  the  next  trial; 


332  BEGUELIN. 

thus  he  adopts  one  of  D'Alembert's  errors.  He  considers  that  if 
the  chances  would  have  been  equal  according  to  the  ordinary 
theory,  then  when  an  event  has  happened  t  times  in  succession 
it  is  ^  +  1  to  1  that  it  will  fail  at  the  next  trial. 

(314.     Beguelin  applies  his  notions  to  the  Petersburg  Problem. 

n 
Suppose  there  are  to  be  n  trials ;  then  instead  of  3  which  the 

common  theory  gives  for  the  expectation  Beguelin  arrives  at 
112  2'  2'  2"-' 


2"^2"^2  +  l'^2.3  +  l^[4  +  l      •••      l^-l  +  l' 

The  terms  of  this  series  rapidly  diminish,  and  the  sum  to 
infinity  is  about  2 J. 

615.  Besides  the  above  result  Beguelin  gives  five  other 
solutions  of  the  Petersburg  Problem.  His  six  results  are  not 
coincident,  but  they  all  give  a  small  finite  value  for  the  expecta- 
tion instead  of  the  large  or  infinite  value  of  the  common  theory. 

616.  The  memoir  does  not  appear  of  any  value  whatever; 
Beguelin  adds  nothing  to  the  objections  urged  by  D'Alembert 
against  the  common  theory,  and  he  is  less  clear  and  interesting. 
It  should  be  added  that  Montucla  appears  to  have  formed  a 
different  estimate  of  the  value  of  the  memoir.  He  says,  on  his 
page  403,  speaking  of  the  Petersburg  Problem, 

Ce  probleme  a  6te  aussi  le  siijet  de  savantes  considerations  metapliy- 
siques  pour  Beguelin... ce  metaphysicien  et  analyste  examine  au  flam- 
beau d'une  metapliysique  profonde  plusieurs  questions  sur  la  nature  du 
calcul  des  probabilites... 

617.  We  have  next  to  notice  a  memoir  which  has  attracted 
considerable  attention.  It  is  entitled  An  Inquiry  into  the  pro- 
bable Parallax,  and  Magnitude  of  the  fixed  Stars,  from  the  Quantity 
of  Light  which  they  afford  us,  and  the  particidar  Circumstances  of 
their  Situation,  by  the  Rev.  John  Michell,  B.D.,  F.RS. 

This  memoir  was  published  in  the  Philosophical  Transactions, 
Vol.  LVII.  Part  I.,  which  is  the  volume  for  1767 :  the  memoir 
occupies  pages  234 — 264. 


MICHELL.  333 

(il8.  The  part  of  the  memoir  with  which  we  are  concerned 
is  that  in  which  Michell,  from  the  fact  that  some  stars  are  very 
close  together,  infers  the  existence  of  design.  His  method  ^vill  be 
seen  from  the  following  extract.     He  says,  page  243, 

Let  us  then  examine  what  it  is  jDrobable  would  have  been  the  least 
apj)arent  distance  of  any  two  or  more  stars,  any  where  in  the  whole 
heavens,  ui^on  the  supposition  that  they  had  been  scattered  by  mere 
chance,  as  it  might  happen.  Now  it  is  manifest,  upon  this  supposition, 
that  every  star  being  as  likely  to  be  in  any  one  situation  as  another, 
the  probability,  that  any  one  particular  star  should  happen  to  be  within 
a  certain  distance  (as  for  example  one  degree)  of  any  other  given  star, 
would  be  represented  (according  to  the  common  way  of  computing 
chances)  by  a  fraction,  whose  numerator  would  be  to  it's  denominator, 
as  a  circle  of  one  degree  radius,  to  a  circle,  whose  racUus  is  the  diameter 
of  a  great  circle  (this  last  quantity  being  equal  to  the  whole  surface  of 

the  sphere)  that  is,  by  the  fraction  .        ..[^,  ^  j  or,  reducing  it  to  a  deci- 

(  Oo  /  D'O  ) 

mal  form,  -000076154  (that  is,  about  1  in  13131)  and  the  complement 

13130 
of  this  to  unity,  viz.  -999923846,   or  the  fraction  y^Yqt  will  represent 

1 0 1  Ox 

the  probability  that  it  would  not  be  so.  But,  because  there  is  the  same 
chance  for  any  one  star  to  be  within  the  distance  of  one  degree  from 
any  given  star,  as  for  every  other,  multiiDlying  this  fraction  into  itself 
as  many  times  as  shall  be  equivalent  to  the  whole  number  of  stars,  of 
not  less  brightness  than  those  in  question,  and  jDutting  oi  for  this  number, 

(-999923846)",  or  the  fraction  (^|^)"  will  represent  the  probability, 

that  no  one  of  the  whole  number  of  stars  n  would  be  within  one  de- 
gree from  the  proposed  given  star ;  and  the  complement  of  this  quan- 
tity to  unity  will  represent  the  probability,  that  there  would  be  some 
one  star  or  more,  out  of  the  whole  number  oi,  within  the  distance  of 
one  degree  from  the  given  star.  And  farther,  because  the  same  event 
is  equally  likely  to  ha^Dpen  to  any  one  star  as  to  any  other,  and  there- 
fore any  one  of  the  whole  number  of  stars  7i  might  as  well  have  been 
taken  for  the  given  star  as  any  other,  we  must  again  repeat  the  last 
found  chance  n  times,  and  consequently  the  number  {('999923846)"}", 

r/13130\")" 
or  the    fraction  I  (  ^kj^.  )  [    will  represent  the   probability,    that  no 

where,  in  the  whole  heavens,  any  two  stars,  amongst  those  in  question, 
would  be  within  the  distance  of  one  degi-ee  from  each  other;  and  the 


S34<  MICHELL. 

complement  of  this  quantity  to  unity  will  represent  tlie  probability  of 
the  contrary. 

619.     Michell  obtains  the  following  results  on  his  page  246, 

If  now  we  compute,  according  to  the  principles  above  laid  down, 
what  the  probability  is,  that  no  two  stars,  in  the  whole  heavens,  should 
have  been  within  so  small  a  distance  from  each  other,  as  the  two  stars 
P  Capricorni,  to  which  I  shall  suppose  about  230  stars  only  to  be  equal 
in  brightness,  we  shall  find  it  to  be  about  80  to  1. 

For  an  example,  where  more  than  two  stars  are  concerned,  we  may 
take  the  six  brightest  of  the  Pleiades,  and,  supj)osing  the  whole  number 
of  those  stars,  which  are  equal  in  splendor  to  the  faintest  of  these,  to 
be  about  1500,  we  shall  find  the  odds  to  be  near  500000  to  1,  that  no 
six  stars,  out  of  that  number,  scattered  at  random,  in  the  whole  hea- 
vens, would  be  within  so  small  a  distance  from  each  other,  as  the  Plei- 
ades are. 

Michell  ofi ves  the  details  of  the  calculation  in  a  note. 


620.  Laplace  alludes  to  Michell  in  the  Theorie . . .  des  Proh., 
page  LXiii.,  and  in  the  Connaissa^ice  des  Terns  for  1815,  page  219. 

621.  The  late  Professor  Forbes  wrote  a  very  interesting  criti- 
cism on  Michell's  memoir;  see  the  London,  Edinhui^gh  and  Buhlin 
Philosophical  Magazine,  for  August  181^9  and  December  1850.  He 
objects  with  great  justice  to  Michell's  mathematical  calculations, 
and  he  also  altogether  distrusts  the  validity  of  the  inferences 
drawn  from  these  calculations. 

« 

622.  Struve  has  given  some  researches  on  this  subject  in  his 
Catalogus  Kovus  Stellarum  Duplicium  et  Midtipliciiim  . . .  Dorpati, 
1827,  see  the  pages  xxxvii. — XLVIII.  Struve's  method  is  very 
different  from  Michell's.  Let  n  be  the  number  of  stars  in  a  given 
area  S  of  the  celestial  surface ;  let  (/>  represent  the  area  of  a  small 

circle  of  x"  radius.     Then  Struve  takes ^ — -    ^  as  the  chance 

of  having  a  pair  of  the  n  stars  within  the  distance  x",  supposing 
that  the  stars  are  distributed  by  chance.  Let  8  represent  the 
surface  beginning  from  —15''  of  declination  and  extending  to  the 
north  pole;  let  n  =  10229,  and  ic  =  4  :  then  Struve  finds  the  above 
expression  to  become  '007814. 


JOHN   BERNOULLI.  335 

See  also  Struve's  SteUarum  Duplicium  et  Multiplicium  Men- 
surce  Micrometricce  ...Petrop.  1837,  page  xci.,  and  his  SteUarum 
Fixarum  ...  Positiones  Medice  ...  Petroj:^.  1852,  page  CLXXXViii. 

Sir  John  Herschel  in  his  Outlines  of  Astronomy ,  1849,  page  565, 
ofives  some  numerical  results  which  are  attributed  to  Struve ;  but 
I  conclude  that  there  is  some  mistake,  for  the  results  do  not 
appear  to  agree  with  Struve's  calculations  in  the  works  above  cited. 

628.  For  a  notice  of  some  of  the  other  subjects  discussed  in 
Michell's  memoir,  see  Struve's  Etudes  d'Astronomie  Stellaire, 
St  Peter shourg,  1847. 

624.  We  have  next  to  notice  another  memoir  by  John  Ber- 
noulli ;  it  is  entitled  Memoire  sur  un  prohleme  de  la  Doctrine  du 
Hazard. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  volume  of  the  Histoire  de 
V Acad. ...  Berlin  for  1768;  the  date  of  publication  is  1770:  the 
memoir  occupies  pages  384 — 408. 

The  problem  discussed  may  be  thus  generally  enunciated. 
Suppose  n  men  to  marry  7i  women  at  the  same  time  ;  find  the 
chance  that  when  half  the  2n  people  are  dead  all  the  marriages 
will  be  dissolved ;  that  is,  find  the  chance  that  all  the  survivors 
will  be  widows  or  widowers.  John  Bernoulli  makes  two  cases ; 
first,  when  there  is  no  limitation  as  to  those  who  die ;  second,  when 
half  of  those  who  die  are  men  and  half  women. 

The  memoir  presents  nothing  of  interest  or  importance  ;  the 
formulas  are  obtained  by  induction  from  particular  cases,  but  are 
not  really  demonstrated. 

625.  We  have  next  to  notice  a  memoir  by  Lambert,  en- 
titled Exameri  d'une  espece  de  Superstition  ramenee  au  calcul 
des  prohahilites. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  volume  for  1771  of  the 
Nouveaux  Memoir es  ...  Berlin ;  the  date  of  publication  is  1773: 
the  memoir  occupies  pages  411 — 420. 

626.  Lambert  begins  by  adverting  to  the  faith  which  many 
people  in  Germany  had  in  the  predictions  of  the  almanack  makers 
respecting  the  weather  and  other  events.     This  suggests  to  him  to 


336  LAMBERT. 

consider  what  is  the  chance  that  the  predictions  will  be  verified 
supposing  the  predictions  to  be  thrown  out  at  random. 

The  problem  which  he  is  thus  led  to  discuss  is  really  the  old 
problem  of  the  game  of  Treize,  though  Lambert  does  not  give  this 
name  to  it,  or  cite  any  preceding  writers  except  Euler's  memoir  of 
1751 :  see  Arts.  162,  280,  430. 

627.  We  may  put  the  problem  thus  :  suppose  n  letters  to  be 
written  and  n  corresponding  envelopes  to  be  directed  ;  the  letters 
are  put  at  random  into  the  envelopes :  required  the  chance  that 
all,  or  any  assigned  number,  of  the  letters  are  placed  in  the  wrong 
envelopes. 

The  total  number  of  ways  in  which  the  letters  can  be  put  into 
the  envelopes  is    n.     There  is  only  one  way  in  which  all  can  be 

placed  in  the  right  envelopes.  There  is  no  way  in  which  just  one 
letter  is  in  the  wrong  envelope.  Let  us  consider  the  number  of 
ways  in  which  just  two  letters  are  in  the  wrong  envelopes :  take 

a  pair  of  letters ;  this  can  be  done  in  — ^- — ^-^  ways  j  then  find 

in  how  many  ways  this  pair  can  be  put  in  the  wrong  envelopes 

without  disturbing  the  others  :  this  can  only  be  done  in  one  way. 

Next  consider  in  how  many  ways  just  three  letters  can  be  put  in 

the  wrong  envelopes ;  take  a  triad  of  letters ;  this  can  be  done 

7X  in 1 )  in 2 ) 

in  -^    L  \ ways,   and  the  selected  triad  can  be  put  in 

wrong  envelopes  in  2  ways,  as  will  be  seen  on  trial. 
Proceeding  thus  we  obtain  the  following  result, 

A  A  ^       ^    (*^  —   1) 


A    ^  (^  -  1)  (^  -  ^)  A     \jl 


1.2.3 

where  A^  expresses  the  number  of  ways  in  which  r  letters,  for 
which  there  are  r  appropriate  envelopes,  can  all  be  placed  in  wrong 
envelopes.     And 

Ao  =  ^,  A^  =  \),  A^=l,  A^  =  2,  .., 

Now  Aq,  A^,  A^,  ...  are  independent  of  7i ;  thus  we  can  deter- 
mine them  by  putting  for  w  in  succession  the  values  1,  2,  3, ...   in 


LAMBERT.  S37 

the  above  identity.     This  last  remark  is  in  fact  the  novelty  of 
Lambert's  memoir. 

Lambert  gives  the  general  law  which  holds  among  the  quan- 
tities -4j,  A^,  ... ,  namely 

A,=  rA,_^+(-iy (2). 

He  does  not  however  demonstrate  that  this  law  holds.  "We 
have  demonstrated  it  implicitly  in  the  value  which  we  have  found 
for  (f)  {n)  in  Art.  161. 

We  get  by  this  law 

A,  =  9,    X=44,    ^,  =  265,    ^7=1854,    A=  14833, ... 

We  can  however  easily  demonstrate  the  law  independently  of 
Art.  161. 


T  \V  —  1 ) 

Let  A**  I  0  stand  for  \r  —  r  r  —  \  -\ ^^^ — ^ 


r-2- 


so  that  the  notation  is  analogous  to  that  which  is  commonly  used 
in  Finite  Differences.  Then  the  fundamental  relation  (1)  sug- 
gests that 

^.  =  A-[0; (3), 

and  we  can  shew  that  this  is  the  case  by  an  inductive  proof  For 
we  find  by  trial  that 

A"Lo  =  Lo  =  i  =  A> 

A^  [0  =  1  -1=0  =  ^,, 
A^[0=  2  -2  +  1=^,; 

and  then  from  the  fundamental  relation  (1)  it  follows  that  if 
-4^  =  A**  [0  for  all  values  of  r  up  to  w  —  1  inclusive,  then  A^  =  A"  [0. 
Thus  (3)  is  established,  and  from  (3)  we  can  immediately  shew 
that  (2)  holds. 

628.  We  now  come  to  another  memoir  by  the  writer  whom  we 
have  noticed  in  Art.  597.  The  memoir  is  entitled  Sur  le  Calcul 
des  Prohahilites,  par  Mr.  Mallet,  Prof.  d'Astronomie  a  Geneve. 

This  memoir  is  published  m  the  Acta  Helvetica ...  Basilece, 
Vol.  VII. ;  the  date  of  publication  is  1772  :  the  memoir  occupies 
pages  133—163. 

22 


338  MALLET. 

629.  The  memoir  consists  of  the  discussion  of  two  problems  r 
the  first  is  a  problem  given  in  the  Ars  Conjectandi  of  James  Ber- 
noulli ;  the  other  relates  to  a  lottery. 

630.  The  problem  from  the  Ars  Conjectandi  is  that  which 
is  given  on  page  161  of  the  work ;  we  have  given  it  in  Art.  117. 

Mallet  notices  the  fact  that  James  Bernoulli  in  addition  to 
the  correct  solution  gave  another  which  led  to  a  different  result 
and  was  therefore  wrong,  but  which  appeared  plausible.  Mallet 
then  says, 

Mr.  Bernoulli  s'etant  contente  d'indiquer  cette  singularity  apparente, 
sans  en  donner  Texplication,  j'ai  cru  qu'il  ne  seroit  pas  inutile  d'entrer 
dans  un  plus  grand  detail  ladessus,  pour  eclaircir  parfaitement  cette 
petite  difficulte,  on  verra  qu'on  peut  imaginer  une  infinite  de  cas  sem- 
hlables  a  celui  de  Mr.  Bernoulli,  dans  la  solution  desquels  il  seroit  aussi 
aise  d'etre  induit  en  erreur. 

631.  Mallet's  remarks  do  not  appear  to  offer  any  thing  new  or 
important ;  he  is  an  obscure  writer  for  want  of  sufficiently  develop- 
ing his  ideas.  The  following  illustration  was  suggested  on  reading 
his  memoir,  and  may  be  of  service  to  a  student.  Suppose  we 
refer  to  the  theory  of  duration  of  life.  Let  abscissae  measured 
from  a  fixed  point  denote  years  from  a  certain  epoch,  and  the  cor- 
responding ordinates  be  proportional  to  the  number  of  survivors 
out  of  a  large  number  born  at  the  certain  epoch.  Now  suppose  we 
wish  to  know  whether  it  is  more  probable  than  not  that  a  new 
born  infant  will  live  more  than  n  years.  James  Bernoulli's  plausi- 
ble but  false  solution  amounts  to  saying  that  the  event  is  more 
probable  than  not,  provided  the  abscissa  of  the  centre  of  gravity  of 
the  area  is  greater  than  n :  the  true  solution  takes  instead  of  the 
abscissa  of  the  centre  of  gravity  the  abscissa  which  corresponds  to 
the  ordinate  bisecting  the  area  of  the  curve.     See  Art.  485. 

632.  We  pass  to  Mallet's  second  problem  which  relates  to  a 
certain  lottery. 

The  lottery  is  that  which  was  called  by  Montmort  la  lotterie 
de  Loraine,  and  which  he  discussed  in  his  work ;  see  his  pages 
257—260,  313,  317,  326,  346.  The  following  is  practically  the 
form  of  the  lottery.     The  director  of  the  lottery  issues  n  tickets  to 


MALLET.  339 

n  persons,  charging  a  certain  sum  for  each  ticket.  He  retains  for 
himself  a  portion  of  the  money  which  he  thus  receives,  say  a ;  the 
remainder  he  distributes  into  n  prizes  which  will  be  gained  by 
those  who  bought  the  tickets.  He  also  offers  a  further  inducement 
to  secure  buyers  of  his  tickets,  for  he  engages  to  return  a  sum,  say 
5,  to  every  ticket-holder  who  does  not  gain  a  prize.  The  jDrizes  are 
distributed  in  the  following  manner.  In  a  box  are  placed  n  coun- 
ters numbered  respectively  from  1  to  n.  A  counter  is  drawn,  and 
a  prize  assigned  to  the  ticket-holder  whose  number  corresponds  to 
the  number  of  the  counter.  The  counter  is  then  replaced  in  the  box. 
Another  drawing  is  made  and  a  prize  assigned  to  the  corresponding 
ticket-holder.  The  counter  is  then  replaced  in  the  box.  This  pro- 
cess is  carried  on  until  n  drawings  have  been  made  ;  and  the  prizes 
are  then  exhausted. 

Hence,  owing  to  the  peculiar  mode  of  drawing  the  lottery,  one 
person  might  gain  more  than  one  prize,  or  even  gain  them  all ;  for 
the  counter  which  bears  his  number  might  be  drawn  any  number 
of  times,  or  even  every  time. 

The  problem  proposed  is  to  find  the  advantage  or  disadvantage 
of  the  director  of  the  lottery. 

633.  Montmort  solved  the  problem  in  the  following  manner. 
Consider  one  of  the  ticket-holders.  The  chance  that  this  per- 
son's  number   is   never    drawn  throughout  the  whole  process  is 

)  .     If  it  is  not  drawn  he  is  to  receive  h  from  the  director ; 

so  that  his  corresponding  expectation  is  h  ( J  •  ^  similar  ex- 
pectation exists  for  each  of  the  ticket-holders,  and  the  sum  of  these 
expectations  is  the  amount  by  which  the  director's  gain  is  di- 
minished.    Thus  the  director's  advantage  is 

a  —  nh  I j  . 

In  the  case  which  Montmort  notices  h  was  equal  to  a,  and  n 
was  20000 ;  thus  the  director's  advantage  was  negative,  that  is,  it 
was  really  a  disadvantage.  Before  Montmort  made  a  complete 
investigation  he  saw  that  the  director's  position  was  bad,  and  he 

22—2 


340  MALLET. 

suspected   that  there  was   a   design  to  cheat   the   public,  which 
actually  happened. 

634.  Mallet  makes  no  reference  to  any  preceding  writer  on 
the  subject ;  but  solves  the  problem  in  a  most  laborious  manner. 
He  finds  the  chances  that  the  number  of  persons  without  prizes 
should  be  1,  or  2,  or  3,  . . .  up  to  n ;  then  he  knows  the  advantage 
of  the  banker  corresponding  to  each  case  by  multiplying  the 
chance  by  the  gain  in  that  case ;  and  by  summing  the  results  he 
obtains  the  total  advantage. 

635.  One  part  of  Mallet's  process  amounts  to  investigating 
the  following  problem.  Suppose  a  die  with  r  faces ;  let  it  be 
thrown  s  times  in  succession :  required  the  chance  that  all  the 
faces  have  appeared.  The  number  of  ways  in  which  the  desired 
event  can  happen  is 

and  the  chance  is  obtained  by  dividing  this  number  by  r'. 

This  is  De  Moivre's  Problem  xxxix  ;  it  was  afterwards  dis- 
cussed by  Laplace  and  Euler  ;  see  Art.  448. 

Mallet  would  have  saved  himself  and  his  readers  great  labour 
if  he  had  borrowed  De  Moivre's  formula  and  demonstration.  But 
he  proceeds  in  a  different  way,  which  amounts  to  what  we  should 
now  state  thus  :  the  number  of  ways  in  which  the  desired  event 
can  happen  is  the  product  of  [r  by  the  sum  of  all  the  homogeneous 
products  of  the  degree  s  —  r  which  can  be  formed  of  the  numbers 
1,  2,  3,  ...  7\  He  does  not  demonstrate  the  truth  of  this  statement ; 
he  merely  examines  one  very  easy  case,  and  says  without  offering 
any  evidence  that  the  other  cases  will  be  obtained  by  following  the 
same  method.     See  his  page  144. 

Mallet  after  giving  the  result  in  the  manner  we  have  just  indi- 
cated proceeds  to  transform  it ;  and  thus  he  arrives  at  the  same 
formula  as  we  have  quoted  from  De  Moivre.  Mallet  does  not 
demonstrate  the  truth  of  his  transformation  generally;  he  contents 
himself  with  taking  some  simple  cases. 

636.     The    transformation   to   which   we    have  just   alluded, 


IVIALLET.  341 

involves  some  algebraical  work  which  we  will  give,  since  as  we 
have  intimated  Mallet  himself  omits  it. 

Let  there  be  r  quantities  a,h,c,  ...  h.     Suppose  x^  to  be  di- 
vided by  (x  —  a)  (x  —  b)  (x  —  c)  ...  {x  —  h).     The  quotient  will  be 

x'-"  +  H^  x^-'  +  H^  x^-'^  +  . . .  in  infinitum, 

where  E^  denotes  the  sum  of  all  the  homogeneous  products  of  the 
degree  r  which  can  be  formed  from  the  quantities  a,h,c,  ...  Ic.  This 
can  be  easily  shewn  by  first  dividing  a;^  by  x  —  a]  then  dividing 

the  result  by  x  —  h,  that  is  multiplying  it  by  a?~M  1 J    ,  and 

so  on. 

Again,  if  ^  be  not  less  than  r  the  expression 

x^ 


(x  —  a)  (x—b)  ...  (x  —  k) 


will  consist  of  an  integral  part  and  a  fractional  part ;  if  ^  be  less 
than  r  there  will  be  no  integral  part.  In  both  cases  the  fractional 
part  will  be 

ABC  K 


X  —  a     x  —  b     x  —  c  x  —  k' 

where  A  = 


a" 


(a  —  b)(a  —  c),..  (a  —  k)^ 

and  similar  expressions  hold  for  B,  C, ...  K.     Now  expand  each  of 

A  B 

the  fractions ,    7 ,  . . .  according  to  negative  powers  of  x ; 

X  "~"  a     X  ~~  0 

and  equate  the  coefficient  of  £c~*~^  to  the  coefficient  in  the  first 

form  which  we  gave  for  x^ -^[(x  —  a)  (x  —  b)  ...  (x  —  k)].     Thus 


Aa'+BU+  Cc'  +  ...  +  Kk'  =  E, 


?-*•+«+!• 


Put  m  for  ^  —  r  +  ^  +  1 ;  then  p  +  ^  =  m  +  r  —  1;  thus  we  may 
express  our  result  in  the  following  words :  the  sum  of  the  homoge- 
neous products  of  the  degree  m,  which  can  be  formed  of  the  r  quan- 
tities a,  b,  c,  ...  k,  is  equal  to 


m+r-l  7,m+r- 1 


+  77 TTI ^ 77 fT+  ... 


(a  — b)  (a  — c)  ...  (a  —  k)      (b —a)  (b  —  c)  ...  (b  —  k) 


o 


12  MALLET. 


This  is  the  general  theorem  which  Mallet  enunciates;  but  only 
demonstrates  in  a  few  simple  cases. 

If  we  put  1,  2,  3, ...  r  respectively  for  a,  h,  c,  .,,k  we  obtain 
the  theorem  by  which  we  pass  from  the  formula  of  Mallet  to  that 
of  De  Moivre,  namely,  the  sum  of  the  homogeneous  products  of 
the  degree  s  —  r  which  can  be  formed  of  the  numbers  1,  2,  ...  r  is 
equal  to 

ij._,,_.,,rfc3),..,_r(t^«fcS,_a,.,...), 

The  particular  case  in  which  s  —  r+l  gives  us  the  following 

result, 

l+2  +  S-\-  ...+r 

,^(r-l)  r(r^l)(r-  2)  ^^,  ] 

+      1.2      ^"^     ^^  1.2.3         ^"^      ^^      ^"V 

which  is  a  known  result. 

687.  When  Mallet  has  finished  his  laborious  investigation  he 
says,  very  justly,  il  y  a  apparence  que  celui  qui  fit  cette  Lotterie  ne 
setoit  pas  donne  la  peine  defaire  tons  les  calculs pr^cedens. 

638.  Mallet's  result  coincides  with  that  which  Montmort  gave, 
and  this  result  being  so  simple  suggested  that  there  might  be  an 
easier  method  of  arriving  at  it.  Accordingly  Mallet  gives  another 
solution,  in  which  like  Montmort  he  investigates  directly  not  the 
advantage  of  the  director  of  the  lottery,  but  the  expectation  of  each 
ticket-holder.  But  even  this  solution  is  more  laborious  than  Mont- 
mort's,  because  Mallet  takes  separately  the  case  in  which  a  ticket- 
holder  has  1,  or  2,  or  3,  . . .  ,  or  ?^  prizes ;  while  in  Montmort's 
solution  there  is  no  necessity  for  this. 

639.  Mallet  gives  the  result  of  the  following  problem  :  Re- 
quired the  chance  that  in  p  throws  with  a  die  of  n  faces  a  specified 
face  shall  appear  just  m  times.     The  chance  is 

\m   p  —m         n^ 


WILLIAM   EMERSON.  34;3 

The  formula  explains  itself;  for  the  chance  of  throwing  the 
specified  face  at  each  throw  is  -,  and  the  chance  of  not  throwing 

71  —  1 

it  is  .     Hence  by  the  fundamental  principles  of  the  subject 

the  chance  of  having  the  specified  face  just  m  times  in  p  throws  is 


I  m  \p  —  m  \nj 


n 


Since  the  whole  number  of  cases  in  the  p  throws  is  if,  it  follows 
that  the  number  of  cases  in  which  the  required  event  can  happen  is 

P 


I  m  I  p  —  m 


(n  -  1) 


p-m  . 


and  the  result  had  been  previously  given   by  Montmort  in  this 
form  :  see  his  page  307. 

640.  On  the  whole  we  may  say  that  Mallet's  memoir  shews 
the  laborious  industry  of  the  writer,  and  his  small  acquaintance 
with  preceding  works  on  the  subject. 

641.  William  Emerson  published  in  1776  a  volume  entitled 
Miscellanies,  or  a  Miscellaneous  Treatise ;  containing  several  Mathe- 
matical Subjects. 

The  pages  1 — 48  are  devoted  to  the  Laws  of  Chance.  These 
pages  form  an  outline  of  the  subject,  illustrated  by  thirty-four 
problems.  There  is  nothing  remarkable  about  the  work  except 
the  fact  that  in  many  cases  instead  of  exact  solutions  of  the 
problems  Emerson  gives  only  rude  general  reasoning  which  he 
considers  may  serve  for  approximate  solution.  This  he  himself 
admits ;  he  says  on  his  page  47, 

It  may  be  observed,  that  in  many  of  these  problems,  to  avoid  more 
intricate  methods  of  calculation,  I  have  contented  myself  with  a  more 
lax  method  of  calculating,  by  which  I  only  approach  near  the  truth. 

See  also  the  Scholium  on  his  page  21. 

Thus  Emerson's  work  would  be  most  dangerous  for  a  beginner 
and  quite  useless  for  a  more  advanced  student. 

We  may  remark  that  pages  49 — 138  of  the  volume  are  devoted 
to  Annuities  and  Insurances. 


S4i4i  BUFFON". 

642.  We  have  now  to  examine  a  contribution  to  our  subject 
from  the  illustrious  naturalist  Buffon  whose  name  has  already- 
occurred  in  Art.  85 -i. 

Buffon's  Ussai  d' Arithmetique  Morale  appeared  in  1777  in  the 
fourth  volume  of  the  Supplement  a  VHistoire  Naturelle,  where  it 
occupies  103  quarto  pages.  Gouraud  says  on  his  page  54,  that  the 
Essay  was  composed  about  1760. 

643.  The  essay  is  divided  into  35  sections. 

Buffon  says  that  there  are  truths  of  different  kinds  ;  thus  there 
are  geometrical  truths  which  we  know  by  reasoning,  and  physical 
truths  which  we  know  by  experience ;  and  there  are  truths  which 
we  believe  on  testimony. 

He  lays  down  without  explanation  a  peculiar  principle  with 
respect  to  physical  truths.  Suppose  that  for  n  days  in  succession 
the  Sun  has  risen,  what  is  the  probability  that  it  will  rise  to- 
morrow ? 

Buffon  says  it  is  proportional  to  T~^.     See  his  6th  section. 

This  is  quite  arbitrary ;  see  Laplace  Theoine. .  .des  Prob.  page  XIII. 

644.  He  considers  that  a  probability  measured  by  so  small 
a  fraction  as  cannot  be  distinguished  from  a  zero  proba- 
bility. He  arrives  at  the  result  thus ;  he  finds  from  the  tables 
that  this  fraction  represents  the  chance  that  a  man  56  years 
old  will  die  in  the  course  of  a  day,  and  he  considers  that  such 
a  man  does  practically  consider  the  chance  as  zero.  The  doctrine 
that  a  very  small  chance  is  practically  zero  is  due  to  D'Alembert ; 

see  Art.  472  :  Buffon  however  is  responsible  for  the  value  Yoooo  ' 
see  his  8th  section. 

645.  Buffon  speaks  strongly  against  gambling.  He  says  at 
the  end  of  his  11th  section  : 

Mais  nous  aliens  donner  un  puissant  antidote  centre  le  mal  ^pi- 
demique  de  la  passion  du  jeu,  et  en  meme-temps  quelques  priservatifs 
centre  rillusion  de  cet  art  dangereux. 

He  condemns  all  gambling,  even  such  as  is  carried  on  under 
conditions    usually    considered   fair ;    and    of   course    still   more 


BUFFON.  345 

gambling  in  which  an  advantage  is  ensured  to  one  of  the  parties. 
Thus  for  example  at  a  game  like  Pharaon,  he  says  : 

...  le  banquier  n'est  qu'im  fripon  avoue,  et  le  ponte  une  dupe,  dont 
on  est  convenu  de  ne  se  pas  moquer. 

See  his  12th  section.     He  finishes  the  section  thus  : 

...je  dis  qu'en  general  le  jeu  est  un  pacte  mal-entendu,  un  contrat 
d^savantageux  aux  deux  parties,  dont  I'effet  est  de  rendre  la  perte  tou- 
jours  plus  grande  que  le  gain;  et  d'oter  au  bien  pour  ajouter  au  mal. 
La  demonstration  en  est  aussi  aisee  qu'evidente. 

64iQ.     The  demonstration  then  follows  in  the  ISth  section. 

Buffon  supposes  two  players  of  equal  fortune,  and  that  each 
stakes  half  of  his  fortune.  He  says  that  the  player  who  wins 
will  increase  his  fortune  by  a  third,  and  the  .player  who  loses  will 
diminish  his  by  a  half ;  and  as  a  half  is  greater  than  a  third 
there  is  more  to  fear  from  loss  than  to  hope  from  gain.  Buffon 
does  not  seem  to  do  justice  to  his  own  argument  such  as  it  is. 
Let  a  denote  the  fortune  of  each  player,   and  h  the  sum  staked. 

Then  the  2:ain  is  estimated  by  Buffon  by  the  fraction ,  and 

^  -^  -^  a+b 

the  loss  by  -  ;  but  it  would  seem  more  natural  to  estimate  the 

loss  by  7,  which  of  course  increases  the  excess  of  the  loss 

to  be  feared  over  the  gain  to  be  hoped  for. 

The  demonstration  may  be  said  to  rest  on  the  principle  that 
the  value  of  a  sum  of  money  to  any  person  varies  inversely  as  his 
whole  fortune. 

647.  Buffon  discusses  at  length  the  Petersburg  Problem  which 
he  says  was  proposed  to  him  for  the  first  time  by  Cramer  at 
Geneva  in  1730.  This  discussion  occupies  sections  15  to  20 
inclusive.     See  Art.  389. 

Buffon  offers  four  considerations  by  which  he  reduces  the  ex- 
pectation of  A  from  an  infinite  number  of  crowns  to  about  five 
crowns  only.     These  considerations  are 

(1)  The  fact  that  no  more  than  a  finite  sum  of  money  exists 
to  pay  A.     Buffon  finds  that  if  head  did  not  fall  until  after  the 


24:6  BUFFON. 

twenty-ninth  throw,  more  money  would  be  required  to  pay  A  than 
the  whole  kingdom  of  France  could  furnish. 

(2)  The  doctrine  of  the  relative  value  of  money  which  we 
have  stated  at  the  end  of  the  preceding  Article. 

(3)  The  fact  that  there  would  not  be  time  during  a  life  for 
playing  more  than  a  certain  number  of  games ;  allowing  only 
two  minutes  for  each  game  including  the  time  necessary  for 
paying. 

(4)  The  doctrine  that  any  chance  less  than  is  to  be 

considered  absolutely  zero  :  see  Art.  644. 

Buffon  cites  Fontaine  as  having  urged  the  first  reason :  see 
Arts.  892,  393. 

648.  The  18th  section  contains  the  details  of  an  experiment 
made  by  Buffon  respecting  the  Petersburg  Problem.  He  says  he 
played  the  game  2084  times  by  getting  a  child  to  toss  a  coin  in 
the  air.  These  2084  games  he  says  produced  10057  crowns.  There 
were  1061  games  which  produced  one  crown,  494  which  produced 
two  crowns,  and  so  on.  The  results  are  given  in  De  Morgan's 
Formal  Logic,  page  185,  together  with  those  obtained  by  a  re- 
petition of  the  experiment.  See  also  Cambridge  Philosophical 
Transactions,  Vol.  ix.  page  122. 

649.  The  23rd  section  contains  some  novelties. 

Buffon  begins  by  saying  that  up  to  the  present  time  Arith- 
metic had  been  the  only  instrument  used  in  estimating  probabilities, 
but  he  proposes  to  shew  that  examples  might  be  given  which 
would  require  the  aid  of  Geometry.  He  accordingly  gives  some 
simple  problems  with  their  results. 

Suppose  a  large  plane  area  divided  into  equal  regular  figures, 
namely  squares,  equilateral  triangles,  or  regular  hexagons.  Let 
a  round  coin  be  thrown  down  at  random;  required  the  chance 
that  it  shall  fall  clear  of  the  bounding  lines  of  the  figure,  or  fall 
on  one  of  them,  or  on  two  of  them ;  and  so  on. 

These  examples  only  need  simple  mensuration,  and  we  need 
not  delay  on  them ;  we  have  not  verified  Bufifon's  results. 

Buffon  had  solved  these  problems  at  a  much  earlier  date.  We 
find  in  the  Hist  de  VAcad.  ...Paris  for  1733  a  short  account  of 


BUFFON.  3-i7 

them ;  they  were  communicated  to  the  Academy  in  that  year ; 
see  Art.  354. 

650.  Buffon  then  proceeds  to  a  more  difficult  example  which 
requires  the  aid  of  the  Integi'al  Calculus.  A  large  plane  area  is 
ruled  with  equidistant  parallel  straight  lines ;  a  slender  rod  is 
thrown  down :  required  the  probability  that  the  rod  will  fall  across 
a  line.  Bufifon  solves  this  correctly.  He  then  proceeds  to  con- 
sider what  he  says  might  have  appeared  more  difficult,  namely  to 
determine  the  probability  when  the  area  is  ruled  with  a  second 
set  of  equidistant  parallel  straight  lines,  at  right  angles  to  the 
former  and  at  the  same  distances.  He  merely  gives  the  result, 
but  it  is  wrong. 

Laplace,  without  any  reference  to  Buffi^n,  gives  the  problem  in 
the  T]ieorie..,des  Proh.,  pages  359 — 362. 

The  problem  involves  a  compound  probability ;  for  the  centre 
of  the  rod  may  be  supposed  to  fall  at  any  point  within  one  of 
the  figures,  and  the  rod  to  take  all  possible  positions  by  turning 
round  its  centre :  it  is  sufficient  to  consider  one  figure.  Bufifon  and 
Laplace  take  the  two  elements  of  the  problem  in  the  less  simple 
order ;  we  mil  take  the  other  order. 

Suppose  a  the  distance  of  two  consecutive  straight  lines  of  one 
system,  h  the  distance  of  two  consecutive  straight  lines  of  the 
other  system ;  let  2r  be  the  length  of  the  rod  and  assume  that 
2r  is  less  than  a  and  also  less  than  h. 

Suppose  the  rod  to  have  an  inclination  6  to  the  line  of  length 
a ;  or  rather  suppose  that  the  inclination  Hes  between  6  and 
6  +  dd.  Then  in  order  that  the  rod  may  cross  a  line  its  centre 
must  fall  somewhere  on  the  area 

ah  —  {a  —  2r  cos  6)  {h  —  2r  sin  6), 

that  is  on  the  area 

2r  (a  sin  ^  +  Z*  cos  0)  —  h-^  sin  6  cos  0. 

Hence  the  whole  probability  of  crossing  the  lines  is 
1 2r  {a  sinO  +  b  cos  0)  -  4r^  sin  6  co&6\  dO 


/I 


/• 


hde 


3^8  BUFFON. 

TT 

The  limits  of  6  are  0  and  -^ .     Hence  the  result  is 

4r  {a-\-h)  -  ^^r^ 
t  irah 

li  a  =  h  this  becomes 

8ar  —  4r^ 

2  • 

ira 
Buffon's  result  expressed  in  our  notation  is 

2  (a  —  r)  r 

If  we  have  only  one  set  of  parallel  lines  we  may  suppose 
h  infinite  in  our  s^eneral  result :  thus  we  obtain  — . 

651.  By  the  mode  of  solution  which  we  have  adopted  we 
may  easily  treat  the  case  in  which  2r  is  not  less  than  a  and 
also  less  than  h,  which  Buffon  and  Laplace  do  not  notice. 

Let  h  be  less  than  a.  First  suppose  2r  to  be  greater  than 
h  but  not  greater  than  a.     Then  the  limits  of  6  instead  of  being 

0  and  5-  will  be  0  and  sin"^  — .     Next  suppose  2r  to  be  greater 

than  a.     Then  the  limits  of  0  will  be  cos~^  x-  and  sin"^  ^r-  :  this 

Zr  Zr 

?) 

holds  so  long-  as  cos"^  ^r-  is  less  than  sin"^  —  ,  that  is  so  long  as 
°  zr  Zr 

fJiAiT^—a^)  is  less  than  h,  that  is  so  long  as  2r  is  less  than  ^^{a^  +  h'^), 

which  is  geometrically  obvious. 

652.  Buffon  gives  a  result  for  another  problem  of  the  same 
kind.  Suppose  a  cube  thrown  down  on  the  area;  required  the 
probability  that  it  will  fall  across  a  line.  With  the  same  meaning 
as  before  for  a  and  h,  let  2r  denote  the  length  of  a  diagonal  of 
a  face  of  the  cube.     The  required  probability  is 

I  Lh  -(a-  2r  cos  6)  {h  -  2r  cos  ^)l  dO 


ahdO 


IT 

the  limits  of  6  being  0  and  7- .     Thus  we  obtain 


FUSS.  349 

^         ^ 4  V2         /  _4  («2+Z>)r  V2 -r^  (27r4-4) 

ao  -r 
4 

BufFon  gives  an  incorrect  result. 

653.  The  remainder  of  Buffon's  essay  is  devoted  to  subjects 
unconnected  with  the  Theory  of  Probability.  One  of  the  sub- 
jects is  the  5ca^^5  0/ 7iotof  ton;  Buffon  recommends  the  duodenary 
scale.  Another  of  the  subjects  is  the  unit  of  length :  Buffon  re- 
commends the  length  of  a  pendulum  which  beats  seconds  at  the 
equator.  Another  of  the  subjects  is  the  quadrature  of  the  circle : 
Buffon  pretends  to  demonstrate  that  this  is  impossible.  His  de- 
monstration however  is  worthless,  for  it  would  equally  apply  to 
any  curve,  and  shew  that  no  curve  could  be  rectified  ;  and  this  we 
know  would  be  a  false  conclusion. 

654.  After  the  Essay  we  have  a  large  collection  of  results 
connected  with  the  duration  of  human  life,  which  Buffon  deduced 
from  tables  he  had  formerly  published. 

Buffon's  results  amount  to  expressing  in  numbers  the  following 
formula :  For  a  person  aged  n  years  the  odds  are  as  a  to  5  that 
he  will  live  x  more  years. 

Buffon  tabulates  this  formula  for  all  integral  values  of  n  up 
to  99,  and  for  various  values  of  x. 

After  these  results  follow  other  tables  and  observations  con- 
nected with  them.  The  tables  include  the  numbers  of  births, 
marriages,  and  deaths,  at  Paris,  from  1709  to  1766. 

655.  Some  remarks  on  Buffon's  views  will  be  found  in  Con- 
dorcet's  JEJssai...de  V Analyse... ^^digQ  LXXI.,  and  in  Dugald  Stewart's 
Works  edited  by  Hamilton,  Vol.  i.  pages  369,  616. 

656.  We  have  next  to  notice  some  investigations  by  Fuss 
under  the  following  titles :  Recherches  sur  tin  j^^^oblhne  du  Calcul 
des  Frobahilites  par  Nicolas  Fuss.  Supplement  au  m^moire  sur  un 
prohleme  du  Calcid  des  Prohabilites... 

The  Recherckes...  occupy  pages  81 — 92  of  the  Pars  Postei^or 
of  the  volume  for  1779  of  the  Acta  Acad.  ...Petrop.;  the  date  of 
publication  is  1783. 


350  FUSS. 

The  Supplement...  occupies  pages  91 — 96  of  the  Pars  Posterior 
of  the  volume  for  1780  of  the  Acta  Acad.  ...  Petrop.;  the  date  of 
publication  is  1784. 

The  problem  is  that  considered  by  James  Bernoulli  on  page  161 
of  the  Ars  Conjectandi ;  see  Art.  117. 

In  the  Recherches  . . .  Fuss  solves  the  problem  ;  he  says  he  had 
not  seen  James  Bernoulli's  own  solution  but  obtained  his  know- 
ledge of  the  problem  from  Mallet's  memoir  ;  see  Art.  628.  Fuss 
published  his  solution  because  his  results  differed  from  that 
obtained  by  James  Bernoulli  as  recorded  by  Mallet.  In  the  Sup- 
plement. . .  Fuss  says  that  he  has  since  procured  James  Bernoulli's 
work,  and  he  finds  that  there  are  two  cases  in  the  problem ;  his 
former  solution  agreed  with  James  Bernoulli's  solution  of  one 
of  the  cases,  and  he  now  adds  a  solution  of  the  other  case,  which 
agrees  with  James  Bernoulli's  solution  for  that  case. 

Thus  in  fact  Fuss  would  have  spared  his  two  papers  if  he 
had  consulted  James  Bernoulli's  own  work  at  the  outset.  We  may 
observe  that  Fuss  uses  the  Lemma  given  by  De  Moivre  on  his 
page  39,  but  Fuss  does  not  refer  to  any  previous  writer  for  it ; 
see  Art.  149. 


CHAPTER    XVIL 

CONDOECET. 

657.  CoNDOKCET  was  born  in  17-i3  and  died  in  1794.  He 
wrote  a  work  connected  with  our  subject,  and  also  a  memoir.  It 
will  be  convenient  to  examine  the  work  first,  although  part  of  the 
memoir  really  preceded  it  in  order  of  time. 

658.  The  work  is  entitled  Essai  siir  Vapplication  de  Vanalyse 
a  la  prohctbilite  des  decisions  rendaes  a  la  pluralite  des  voix.  Par 
M.  Le  Ma7^quis  de  Condor cet ...  Paris  1785. 

This  work  is  in  quarto ;  it  consists  of  a  Discours  Preliminaire 
which  occupies  cxci.  pages,  and  of  the  Essai  itself  which  occupies 
304  pages. 

659.  The  object  of  the  Preliminary  Discourse  is  to  give  the 
results  of  the  mathematical  investigations  in  a  form  which  may  be 
intelligible  to  those  who  are  not  mathematicians.  It  commences 
thus : 

Un  grand  homme,  dont  je  regretterai  toujours  les  legons,  les  exem- 
ples,  et  sur-tout  I'amitie,  etoit  persuade  que  les  verites  des  Sciences 
morales  et  politiques,  sent  susceptibles  de  la  meme  certitude  que  celles 
qui  forment  le  systeme  des  Sciences  physiques,  et  meme  que  les  branches 
de  ces  Sciences  qui,  comme  rAstronomie,  paroissent  approcher  de  la 
certitude  mathematique. 

Cette  opinion  lui  etoit  chere,  parce  qu'elle  conduit  a  I'esperance  con- 
solante  que  I'espece  humaine  fera  necessairement  des  progres  vers  le 
bonheur  et  la  perfection,  comme  elle  en  a  fait  dans  la  connoissance  de  la 
verite. 

C'etoit  pour  lui  que  j'avois  entrepris  cet  ouvrage 


852  CONDORCET. 

The  great  man  to  whom  Condorcet  here  refers  is  named  in 
a  note  :  it  is  Turgot. 

Condorcet  himself  perished  a  victim  of  the  French  Revolution, 
and  it  is  to  be  presumed  that  he  must  have  renounced  the  faith 
here  expressed  in  the  necessary  progress  of  the  human  race  to- 
wards happiness  and  perfection. 

660.  Condorcet's  Essai  is  divided  into  five  parts. 

The  Discours  Preliminaire,  after  briefly  expounding  the  funda- 
mental principles  of  the  Theory  of  Probability,  proceeds  to  give 
in  order  an  account  of  the  results  obtained  in  the  five  parts  of 
the  Essai. 

We  must  state  at  once  that  Condorcet's  work  is  excessively 
difficult ;  the  difficulty  does  not  lie  in  the  mathematical  investi- 
gations, but  in  the  expressions  which  are  employed  to  introduce 
these  investigations  and  to  state  their  results :  it  is  in  many  cases 
almost  impossible  to  discover  what  Condorcet  means  to  say.  The 
obscurity  and  self  contradiction  are  without  any  parallel,  so  far  as 
our  experience  of  mathematical  works  extends ;  some  examples 
will  be  given  in  the  course  of  our  analysis,  but  no  amount  of 
examples  can  convey  an  adequate  impression  of  the  extent  of 
the  evils.  We  believe  that  the  work  has  been  very  little  studied, 
for  we  have  not  observed  any  recognition  of  the  repulsive  peculi- 
arities by  which  it  is  so  undesirably  distinguished. 

661.  The  Preliminary  Discourse  begins  with  a  brief  exposition 
of  the  fundamental  principles  of  the  Theory  of  Probability,  in 
the  course  of  which  an  interesting  point  is  raised.  After  giving 
the  mathematical  definition  of  probability,  Condorcet  proposes  to 
shew  that  it  is  consistent  with  ordinary  notions ;  or  in  other  words, 
that  the  mathematical  measure  of  probability  is  an  accurate 
measure  of  our  degree  of  belief  See  his  page  vil.  Unfortunately 
he  is  extremely  obscure  in  his  discussion  of  the  point. 

We  shall  not  delay  on  the  Preliminary  Discourse,  because  it 
is  little  more  than  a  statement  of  the  results  obtained  in  the 
Essay. 

The  Preliminary  Discourse  is  in  fact  superfluous  to  any  person 
who  is  sufficiently  acquainted  with  Mathematics  to  study  the 
Essay,  and  it  would  be  scarcely  intelligible  to  any  other  person. 


CONDOKCET.  353 

For  in  general  when  we  have  no  mathematical  symbols  to  guide 
us  in  discovering  Condorcet's  meaning,  the  attempt  is  nearly 
hopeless. 

We  proceed  then  to  analyse  the  Essay. 

662.  Condorcet's  first  part  is  divided  into  eleven  sections, 
devoted  to  the  examination  of  as  many  Hypotheses ;  this  part 
occupies  pages  1 — 136. 

We  will  consider  Condorcet's  first  Hypothesis. 

Let  there  be  2^  +  1  voters  who  are  supposed  exactly  alike  as  to 
judgment ;  let  v  be  the  probability  that  a  voter  decides  correctly, 
e  the  probability  that  he  decides  incorrectly,  so  that  v-\-e  —  l  ; 
required  the  probability  that  there  will  be  a  majority  in  favour 
of  the  correct  decision  of  a  question  submitted  to  tiie  voters.  We 
may  observe,  that  the  letters  v  and  e  are  chosen  from  commencing 
the  words  lerite  and  eiTeur. 

The  required  probability  is  found  by  expanding  (v  +  e)^^"^^  by 
the  Binomial  Theorem,  and  taking  the  terms  from  v^^'^^  to  that 
which  involves  v^'^^  e^,  both  inclusive.  Two  peculiarities  in  Con- 
dorcet's notation  may  here  be  noticed.  He  denotes  the  required 
probability  by  V^;  this  is  very  inconvenient  because  this  symbol 
has  universally  another  meaning,  namely  it  denotes  V  raised  to 

the  power  q.     He  uses  —  to  denote  the  coefficient  of  ^;""^'e'"  in 

m 

the  expansion  of  (v  +  e)";  this  also  is  very  inconvenient  because 

the  symbol  —  has  universally  another  meaning,  namely  it  denotes 

a  fraction  in  which  the  numerator  is  w  and  the  denominator  is  m. 
It  is  not  desirable  to  follow  Condorcet  in  these  two  innovations.   " 
We  will  denote  the  probability  required  by  </>  (q)  ;  thus 

^  (q)  =  v^^^  +  (2q  +  1)  v'^  e  +  ^^^^^^^"1  v''-' e^  +  . .. 

I  2^  + 1 


663.  The  expression  for  (/>  {q)  is  transformed  by  Condorcet 
into  a  shape  more  convenient  for  his  purpose ;  and  this  trans- 
formation we  will  now   give.     Let  </>  (2'  +  1)   denote  what  ^  {q) 

23 


S54*  CONDOECET. 

becomes  when  q^  is  changed  into  $'  -H  1,  that  is  let  ^  (g  +  1)  denote 
the  probability  that  there  will  be  a  majority  in  favour  of  a  correct 
decision  when  the  question  is  submitted  to  2^'  +  8  voters.  There- 
fore 

<^  (^  +  1)  =  ^,^^-  +  (2^  +  3)  v^-'^ e  +  (?i±|I|i±21  ^...i ,. 


+  ...+ 


2^  +  3 


(7  +  2    q  +  1 


v'"-'  e'^\ 


'     Since  v-\-e  =  l  we  have 

^  (2)  =  («  + «)"  <!>  fe). 

Thus       ^(j  +  l)_,/,(j)  =  ^(2  +  l)_(„  +  e)»^(j). 

Now  (f>  (q  +  1)  consists  of  certain  terms  in  the  expansion  of 
(v  +  ey^^^,  and  cp  (q)  consists  of  certain  terms  in  the  expansion  of 
{v  +  ey^'^^ ;  so  we  may  anticipate  that  in  the  development  of 
(j>  (q+l)  —  (v  +  ey  (j)  (q)  very  few  terms  will  remain  uncancelled. 
In  fact  it  will  be  easily  found  that 

I  2^  +  1  \2q  +  l 


g  +  1  [I  |g  +  l  |g 


2q  +  l 


l+i  [9 


Hence  we  deduce 


^  (^)  =  y  +  (v  -e)  jve  +  ji;V+  J^^'^'+  7V3  ^*^* 


...  +  r==f^v (2). 

664<.  The  result  given  in  equation  (2)  is  the  transformation 
to  which  we  alluded.  We  may  observe  that  throughout  the  first 
part  of  his  Essay,  Condorcet  repeatedly  uses  the  method  of  trans- 
formation just  exemplified,  and  it  also  appears  elsewhere  in  the 
Essay  ;  it  is  in  fact  the  chief  mathematical  instrument  which 
he  employs. 

It  will  be  observed  that  we  assumed  v  +  e  =  l  in  order  to 
obtain  equation  (2).     We  may  however  obtain  a  result  analogous 


COXDORCET.  So  5 

to  (2)  which  shall  be  identically  true,  whatever  v  and  e  may  be. 
We  have  only  to  replace  the  left-hand  member  of  (1)  by 

^(^  +  l)-(v  +  ey<f>(q), 

and  we  can  then  deduce 


q_±l  ^ 


=^v{v  +  ef"  +  (v  -  e)  \ve  {v  +  ey'  +  ?  ^^e^  [v  +  e)^"* 
5  4  1 2a  - 1  1 

1.2^^  [£    [£—  1 

This  is  identically  true ;  if  we  suppose  v-{-e=l,  we  have  the 
equation  (2). 

665.     We  resume  the  consideration  of  the  equation  (2). 

Suppose  V  greater  than  e ;  then  we  shall  find  that  <j)  (q)  =1 
when  q  is  infinite.  For  it  may  be  shewn  that  the  series  in  powers 
of  ve  which  occurs  in   (2)   arises  from  expanding 

in  powers  of  ve  as  far  as  the  term  which  involves  vV.     Thus  when 
q  is  infinite,  we  have 

^(^g^)  =  v  +  {v-e)  1-2  +  2  (1  -^^^)"4- 

Now  1  —  4<ve=  (v+  ef  —  ^ve=  (v  —ey.  Therefore  when  q  is 
infinite 

/         \  {        V  —  e     ,     V  +  6   ] 

—  v+{v  —  e)<—  777 \  +  o^ \C 

^         ^  [     2(v-e)      2{v-  e)} 

=  V  +  e  =  1. 

The  assumption  that  v  is  greater  than  e  is  introduced  when 
we  put  v  —  e  for  (1  —  4re)i 

23—2 


856  CONDORCET. 

Thus  we  have  the  following  result  in  the  Theory  of  Probability  : 
if  the  probability  of  a  correct  decision  is  the  same  for  every  voter 
and  is  greater  than  the  probability  of  an  incorrect  decision,  then 
the  probability  that  the  decision  of  the  majority  will  be  correct 
becomes  indefinitely  nearly  equal  to  unity  by  sufficiently  in- 
creasinof  the  number  of  voters. 

It  need  hardly  be  observed  that  practically  the  hypotheses  on 
which  the  preceding  conclusion  rests  cannot  be  realised,  so  that 
the  result  has  very  little  value.  Some  important  remarks  on  the 
subject  will  be  found  in  Mill's  Logic,  1862,  Vol.  II.  pages  Qo,  Q>Q, 
where  he  speaks  of  ''  misapplications  of  the  calculus  of  probabilities 
which  have  made  it  the  real  opprobrium  of  mathematics." 

666.  We  again  return  to  the  equation  (2)  of  Art.  663. 

If  we  denote  by  -v/r  (^q)  the  probability  that  there  will  be  a 
majority  in  favour  of  an  incorrect  decision,  we  can  obtain  the 
value  of  yfr^q)  from  that  of  ^  (q)  by  interchanging  e  and  v. 

We  have  also  ^  (^)  +  '*/^  fe)  =  1. 

Of  course  if  v  =  e  we  have  obviously  ^(^q)  ='\fr  {q),  for  all 
values  of  q ;  the  truth  of  this  result  when  q  is  infinite  is  esta- 
blished by  Condorcet  in  a  curious  way ;  see  his  page  10. 

667.  We  have  hitherto  spoken  of  the  probability  that  the 
decision  will  be  correct,  that  is  we  have  supposed  that  the  result 
of  the  voting  is  not  yet  known. 

But  now  suppose  we  know  that  a  decision  has  been  given  and 
that  m  voters  voted  for  that  decision  and  n  against  it,  so  that  m 
is  greater  than  n.  We  ask,  what  is  the  probability  that  the  de- 
cision is  correct  ?  Condorcet  says  briefly  that  the  number  of  com- 
binations in  favour  of  the  truth  is  expressed  by 

12^  +  1 


v'^e^ 


and  the  number  in  favour  of  error  by 

12^  +  1 


e'\'". 


m    n 


Thus  the  probabilities  of  the  correctness  and  incorrectness  of  the 
decision  are  respectively 


CONDORCET.  357 


and 


jiijn    I     jni^jn     ^-^-^     ^.tnjn    >     jn^jn 


See  his  page  10. 

668.  The  student  of  Condorcet's  work  must  carefully  dis- 
tinguish between  the  probability  of  the  correctness  of  a  decision 
that  has  been  given  when  we  know  the  numbers  for  and  against, 
and  the  probability  when  we  do  not  know  these  numbers.  Con- 
dorcet  sometimes  leaves  it  to  be  gathered  from  the  context  which 
he  is  considering.  For  example,  in  his  Preliminary  Discourse 
page  XXIII.  he  begins  his  account  of  his  first  Hypothesis  thus  : 

Je  considere  d'abord  le  cas  le  plus  simple,  celui  ou  le  nombre  des 
Votans  etant  impair,  on  prononce  simplemeBt  a  la  plurality. 

Dans  ce  cas,  la  probabilite  de  ne  pas  avoir  uue  decision  fausse,  celle 
d'avoir  une  decision  vraie,  celle  que  la  decision  rendue  est  conforme  a  la 
verite,  sont  les  memes,  puisqu'il  ne  peut  y  avoir  de  cas  oii  il  n'y  ait 
pas  de  decision. 

Here,  although  Condorcet  does  not  say  so,  the  words  celle  que 
la  decision  rendue  est  conforme  a  la  verite  mean  that  we  know 
the  decision  has  been  given,  but  we  do  not  know  the  numbers 
for  and  against.  For,  as  we  have  just  seen,  in  the  Essay  Con- 
dorcet takes  the  case  in  which  we  do  know  the  numbers  for  and 
against,  and  then  the  probability  is  not  the  same  as  that  of  the 
correctness  of  a  decision  not  yet  given.  Thus,  in  short,  in  the 
Preliminary  Discourse  Condorcet  does  not  say  which  case  he  takes, 
and  he  really  takes  the  case  which  he  does  not  consider  in  the 
Essay,  excluding  the  case  which  he  does  consider  in  the  Essay; 
that  is,  he  takes  the  case  which  he  might  most  naturally  have 
been  supposed  not  to  have  taken. 

669.  We  will  now  proceed  to  Condorcet's  second  H3rpothesis 
out  of  his  eleven ;  see  his  page  14. 

Suppose,  as  before,  that  there  are  2q  -\-l  voters,  and  that  a 
certain  plurality  of  votes  is  required  in  order  that  the  decision 
should  be  valid ;  let  2q  +  1  denote  this  plurality. 

Let  </)  (q)  denote  the  terms  obtained  from  the  expansion  of 
(v  +  ey'"-',  from  v'^"-'  to  the  term  which  involves  t*^'-^^^  e^'^,  both 
inclusive.  Let  yfr  (^)  be  formed  from  </>  (q)  by  interchanging  e 
and  V. 


358  CONDORCET. 

Then  (f>  (q)  -^'^  (q)  is  the  probability  that  there  will  be  a  valid 
decision,  <^  (q)  is  the  probability  that  there  will  be  a  valid  and 
correct  decision,  and  yjr  (q)  is  the  probability  that  there  will  be  a 
valid  and  incorrect  decision.  Moreover  1  —  -yfr  (q)  is  the  probability 
that  there  will  not  be  an  incorrect  decision,  and  1  —  cj)  {q)  is  the 
probability  that  there  will  not  be  a  correct  decision. 

It  will  be  observed  that  here  0  (q)  +  yjr  (q)  is  not  equal  to  unity. 
In  fact  1  —  <f>  {q)  —  yjr  (q)  consists  of  all  the  terms  in  the  expansion 
of  (v  +  e)'^^^^  lying  between  those  which  involve  v^'^'^'^^  e'^'^'  and 
^«-<z'  g3+2'+i  both  exclusive.  Thus  1  —  cj)  (q)  —  ylr  (q)  is  the  probability 
that  the  decision  will  be  invalid  for  want  of  the  prescribed 
plurality. 

It  is  shewn  by  Condorcet  that  if  v  is  greater  than  e  the 
limit  of  <p  {q)  when  q  increases  indefinitely  is  unity.  See  his 
pages  19 — 21. 

670.  Suppose  we  know  that  a  valid  decision  has  been  given, 
but  do  not  know  the  numbers  for  and  against.  Then  the  pro- 
bability that  the  decisian  is  correct  is    ,  ,  ,       .  ,  ^  ,  and  the  pro- 

bability  that  it  is  incorrect  is         r    ^^ 


<l>iq)+'f{q)' 

Suppose  we  know  that  a  valid  decision  has  been  given,  and 
also  know  the  numbers  for  and  against.  Then  the  probabilities 
of  the  correctness  and  incorrectness  of  the  decision  are  those  which 
have  been  stated  in  Art.  667. 

671.  We  will  now  indicate  what  Condorcet  appears  to  mean 
by  the  principal  conditions  which  ought  to  be  secured  in  a  de- 
cision ;  they  are : 

1.  That  an  incorrect  decision  shall  not  be  given ;  that  is 
l  —  '^iq)  must  be  large. 

2.  That  a  correct  decision  shall  be  given ;  that  is  <p  (q)  must 
be  large. 

3.  That  there  shall  be  a  valid  decision,  correct  or  incorrect ; 
that  is  </)  (2')  +  '^  (q)  must  be  large. 

4.  That  a  valid  decision  which  has   been   given  is  correct, 


CONDORCET.  859 

supposing  the  numbers  for  and  against  not  to  be  known ;  that  is 

.  /  N       .  /  \  must  be  large. 

5.  That  a  vaHd  decision  which  has  been  given  is  correct, 
supposing  the  numbers   for  and   against  to    be  known ;    that  is 

-jjp^^ :j^^-^   must  be   large,  even  when  m  and  7i  are   such  as  to 

give  it  the  least  value  of  which  it  is  susceptible. 

These  appear  to  be  what  Condorcet  means  by  the  principal 
conditions,  and  which,  in  his  usual  fluctuating  manner,  he  calls 
in  various  places  Jive  conditions,  four  conditions,  and  tivo  con- 
ditions.    See  his  pages  xviii,  xxxi,  LXix. 

672.  Before  leaving  Condorcet's  second  Hypothesis  we  will 
make  one  remark.  On  his  page  17  he  requires  the  following 
result. 


{l  +  ^(l_4^)p^(l_4^)      ^'       1     -^  •  1.2 

I  w  +  2r  —  1 

•  •  •  T  ',      ;       ;  T  ^   "!"••• 

7'  \7i  +  r—  I 

On  his  page  18  he  gives  two  ingenious  methods  by  which  the 
result  may  be  obtained  indirectly.  It  may  however  be  obtained 
directly  in  various  ways.  For  example,  take  a  formula  which  may 
be  established  by  the  Differential  Calculus  for  the  expansion  of 
(1  +  \/(l  —  4^)}""^  ii^  powers  of  s,  and  differentiate  with  respect 
to  z,  and  put  n  —  2  for  771. 

673.  Condorcet's  third  Hjrpothesis  is  similar  to  his  second  ; 
the  only  difference  is  that  he  here  supposes  2q  voters,  and  that 
a  plurahty  of  2q  is  required  for  a  valid  decision. 

674<.  In  his  fourth,  fifth,  and  sixth  H^^otheses  Condorcet 
supposes  that  a  plurality  is  required  which  is  proportional,  or 
nearly  so,  to  the  whole  number  of  voters.  We  will  state  the 
results  obtained  in  one  case.  Suppose  we  require  that  at  least 
two-thirds  of  the  whole  number  of  voters  shall  concur  in  order 
that  the  decision  may  be  valid.  Let  n  represent  the  whole  num- 
ber of  voters ;  let  ^  (n)  represent  the  probability  that  there  will 


BOO  CONDORCET. 

be  a  valid   and  correct  decision,  and  -^/r  (n)  the  probability  that 

there  will  be  a  valid  and  incorrect  decision ;  let  v  and  e  have  the 

same  meaning  as  in  Art.  662.     Then,  when  n  is  infinite,  if  v  is 

2  ,        ,  2 

greater  than  ^  we  have  ^  (n)  =1,  if  v  is  less  than  ^  we  have 

2 
0  (w)  =  0 ;  and  similarly  if  e  is  greater  than  ^  >  that  is  if  v  is 

o 

1  .       .  2  . 

less  than  ^ ,  we  have  -^  (n)  =  1,  and  if  e  is  less  than  -^ ,  that  is 
o  o 

if  t;  is  greater  than  ^ ,  we  have  ylr  (n)  ==0. 

o 

We  shall  not  stop  to  give  Condorcet's  own  demonstrations  of 

these  results  ;  it  will  be  sufficient  to  indicate  how  they  may  be 

derived  from  Bernoulli s  Theorem;  see  Art.  123.     We  know  from 

this  theorem  that  when  n  is  very  large,  the  terms  which  are  in 

the   neighbourhood   of  the   greatest   term   of   the   expansion   of 

{v-\-eY  overbalance  the  rest  of  the  terms.     Now  </>  {n)  consists  of 

the  first  third  of  all  the  terms  of  (v  +  e)",  and  thus  if  v  is  greater 

2 
than  -  the  greatest  term  is  included  within  <j>  (n),  and  therefore 

(f>  (n)  =1  ultimately. 

2 
The   same   considerations   shew   that   when    v  =  -^,   we   have 

1       .  ^ 

^(n)  =  ^  ultimately. 

675.  Condorcet's  seventh  and  eighth  Hypotheses  are  thus 
described  by  himself,  on  his  page  xxxiii : 

La  septieme  hypothese  est  celle  ou  I'on  renvoie  la  decision  a  un  autre 
temps,  si  la  pluralite  exigee  n'a  pas  lieu. 

Dans  la  huitieme  hy]^)othese,  on  suppose  que  si  I'assemblee  n'a  pas 
rendu  sa  premiere  decision  a  la  pluralite  exigee,  on  prend  une  seconde 
fois  les  avis,  et  ainsi  de  suite,  jusqu^a  ce  que  Ton  obtienne  cette  pluralite. 

These  two  Hypotheses  give  rise  to  very  brief  discussions  in  the 

Essay. 

676.  The  ninth  Hypothesis  relates  to  the  decisions  formed 
by  various  systems  of  combined  tribunals.  Condorcet  commences 
it  thus  on  his  page  57 : 


CONDORCET.  861 

Jusqu'ici  nous  avons  suppose  iin  seul  Tribunal ;  dans  plusieurs  pays 
cependant  on  fait  juger  la  meme  affaire  par  plusieurs  Tribunaux,  ou 
plusieurs  fois  par  le  meme,  mais  d'apres  une  nouvelle  instruction,  jus- 
qu'^  ce  qu'on  ait  obtenu  un  certain  nombre  de  decisions  conformes. 
Cette  bypotbese  se  subdivise  en  plusieurs  cas  differens  que  nous  aliens 
examiner  separement.  En  effet,  on  peut  exiger,  1".  I'unanimite  de  ces 
decisions ;  2°.  une  certaine  loi  de  pluralite,  formee  ou  par  un  nombre 
absolu,  ou  par  un  nombre  proportionnel  au  nombre  des  decisions 
prises  ;  3^  un  certain  nombre  consecutif  de  decisions  conformes.  Quand 
la  forme  des  Tribunaux  est  telle,  que  la  decision  peut  etre  nulle,  comma 
dans  la  septieme  hypotbese,  il  faut  avoir  ^gard  aux  decisions  nulles. 
Enfin  il  faut  examiner  ces  differens  cas,  en  supposant  le  nombre  de  ces 
decisions  successives,  ou  comme  determine,  ou  comme  indefini. 

677.  The  ninth  Hypothesis  extends  over  pages  57 — 86 ;  it 
appears  to  have  been  considered  of  gi'eat  importance  by  Condorcet 
himself  We  shall  give  some  detail  respecting  one  very  in- 
teresting case  which  is  discussed.  This  case  Condorcet  gives  on 
pages  73 — 86.  Condorcet  is  examining  the  probability  of  the 
correctness  of  a  decision  which  has  been  confirmed  in  succession 
by  an  assigned  number  of  tribunals  out  of  a  series  to  which  the 
question  has  been  referred.  The  essential  part  of  the  discussion 
consists  in  the  solution  of  two  problems  which  we  will  now  enun- 
ciate. Suppose  that  the  probability  of  the  happening  of  an  event 
in  a  single  trial  is  v,  and  the  probability  of  its  failing  is  e,  required, 
1st  the  probability  that  in  r  trials  the  event  will  happen  p  times 
in  succession,  2nd  the  probability  that  in  r  trials  the  event  will 
happen  p  times  in  succession  before  it  fails  p  times  in  succession. 

It  is  the  second  of  these  problems  which  Condorcet  wishes 
to  apply,  but  he  finds  it  convenient  to  begin  with  the  solution 
of  the  first,  which  is  much  the  simpler,  and  which,  as  we  have 
seen,  in  Art.  325,  had  engaged  the  attention  of  De  Moivre. 

678.  We  have  already  solved  the  first  problem,  in  Art.  325, 
but  it  will  be  convenient  to  give  another  solution. 

Let  (/)  {r)  denote  the  probability  that  in  r  trials  the  event  will 
happen^  times  in  succession.     Then  we  shall  have 

^  (r)  =ifJ^v^~'  e<j)(r-p)+  if^e  ^  (r  -^  +  1)  +  ... 

,..+ve(j){r-2)+e(j>{r-l)  (1). 


S62  CONDORCET. 

To  shew  the  truth  of  this  equation  we  observe  that  in  the 
first  p  trials  the  following  p  cases  may  arise ;  the  event  may- 
happen  2^  times  in  succession,  or  it  may  happen  p  —  1  times  in 
succession  and  then  fail,  or  it  may  happen  /:>  -  2  times  in  succes- 
sion and  then  fail,  ,  or  it  may  fail  at  the  first  trial.     The 

aggregate  of  the  probabilities  arising  from  all  these  cases  is  </>  (r). 
The  probability  from  the  first  case  is  v^.  The  probability  from 
the  second  case  is  v^"^  ecj)  (r  —p) :  for  v^"^  e  is  the  probability  that 
the  event  will  happen  p—  \  times  in  succession,  and  then  fail ; 
and  <j>(r  —p)  is  the  probability  that  the  event  will  happen  p 
times  in  succession  in  the  course  of  the  remaining  r—p  trials. 
In  a  similar  way  the  term  ?;^~V  </>  (r  —  p  +  1)  is  accounted  for  ;  and 
so  on.     Thus  the  truth  of  equation  (1)  is  established. 

679.  The  equation  (1)  is  an  equation  in  Finite  Differences ; 
its  solution  is 

*  (r)  =  (7.2/,-+  C,y:+  C^:+  ...+  C,y;+G (2). 

Here  (7^,  C^,  ,..  C^  are  arbitrary  constants  ;  y^  V^y  "-y^  are  the 
roots  of  the  following  equation  in  y, 

y^  =  e{v'-'  +v'-'y  ^v'-'f  +  ,..  +y'-') (8); 

and  C  is  to  be  found  from  the  equation 

0=^^  +  6(t^^-'  +  v^"^+...  +  v  +  l)  C, 

that  is  (7=^^  +  6-1 G\ 

and  as  e  =  1  —  v  we  obtain  (7=  1. 

We  proceed  to  examine  equation  (3).  Put  1—v  for  e,  and 
assume  y  =  -  :  thus 


'"  --^^ «. 

We  shall  shew  that  the  real  roots  of  equation  (3)  are  nu- 
merically less  than  unity,  and  so  also .  arc  the  moduli  of  the  im- 
aginary  roots ;    that   is,   we  shall   shew   that   the   real   roots  of 


CONDORCET.  S63 

equation  (4)  are  numerically  greater  than  v,  and  so  also  are  the 
moduli  of  the  imaginary  roots. 

"We  know  that  v  is  less  than  unity.  Hence  from  (4)  if  z  be 
real  and  positive  it  must  be  greater  than  v.     For  if  z  be  less  than 

V,  then  _ is  less  than  z ,  and  a  fortiori  — ^ ~  is  less 

V 

than  -z .     If  s  be  negative  in  (4)  we  must  have  1  —  z^'  nega- 
tive, so  that  p  must  be  even,  and  z  numerically  greater  than  unity, 
and  therefore  numerically  gi'eater  than  v.     Thus  the  real  roots  of 
(4)  must  be  numerically  greater  than  v. 
Again,  we  may  put  (4)  in  the  form 

v  +  v'  +  v^+  ...  =  z  +  z^-\-  ...+z^ (5). 

Now  suppose  that  z  is  an  imaginary  quantity,  say 

z  =zJc  (cos  d  4-  V—  1  sin  0)  ; 

then  if  k  is  not  greater  than  v,  we  see  by  aid  of  the  theorem 

0"  =  k""  (cos  nd  +  V^  sin  nO), 

that  the  real  terms  on  the  right-hand  side  of  (5)  will  form  an 
aggregate  less  than  the  left-hand  side.  Thus  k  must  be  greater 
than  V. 

After  what  we  have  demonstrated  respecting  the  values  of  the 
roots  of  (3),  it  follows  from  (2)  that  when  r  is  infinite  <f>  (r)  =  1. 

680.     We  proceed  to  the  second  problem. 

Let  (f)  (r)  now  denote  the  probability  that  in  r  trials  the  event 
will  happen  p  times  in  succession  before  it  fails  p  times  in  suc- 
cession. 

Let  ^jr  (n)  denote  the  probability  that  the  event  will  happen 
p  times  in  succession  before  it  fails  p  times  in  succession,  supposing 
that  one  trial  has  just  been  made  in  ivhich  the  event  failed,  and  that 
n  trials  remain  to  be  made. 

Then  instead  of  equation  (1)  we  shall  now  obtain 

^(r)='yP  +  ?;^~'ei/r(r-;?)  +  v''"' eyjr  (r - p  +  1) -{-  ... 

. . .  +  ve^{r  (r-2)  +eylr(r-V)  ...  (6). 
This  equation  is  demonstrated  in  the  same  manner  as  (1)  w^as. 


364  CONDORCET. 

We  have  now  to  shew  the  connexion  between  the  functions 
(j)  and  yjr;  it  is  determined  by  the  following  relation  ; 

'>lr(n)==(l)  (n)  -  e^"^  [cf>  {n-p  +l)-ef  (n-p)} (7). 

To  shew  the  truth  of  this  relation  we  observe  that  yjr  (n)  is 
less  than  <f>  (n)  for  the  following  reason,  and  for  that  alone.  If  the 
one  failure  had  not  taken  place  there  might  be  ^  —  1  failures  in 
succession,  and  there  would  still  remain  some  chance  of  the 
happening  of  the  event  p  times  in  succession  before  its  failing 
p  times  in  succession ;  since  the  one  failure  has  taken  place  this 
chance  is  lost.     The  corresponding  probability  is 

e^-'  {(f>  (n  -p  +  1)-  ef  {n  -p)}. 

The  meaning  of  the  factor  e^~^  is  obvious,  so  that  we  need  only 
explain  the  meaning  of  the  other  factor.  And  it  will  be  seen 
that  (j)  (n  —  p  -h  1)  —  eyjr  {n  —  p))  expresses  the  probability  of  the 
desired  result  in  the  n—p  +  1  trials  which  remain  to  be  made; 
for  here  the  rejected  part  eyjr{n—p)  is  that  part  which  would 
coexist  with  failure  in  the  first  of  these  remaininof  trials,  which 
part  would  of  course  not  be  available  when  p—1  failures  had 
already  taken  place. 

Thus  we  may  consider  that  (7)  is  established. 

In  (6)  change  r  into  r  —p ;  therefore 

^  (r-p)  =  v^  +  v'^'^ef  {r-2p)  +  if-' e^^r  [r-2p-\-V)  +  ... 

. . .  +  ve-^  (r  —p  —  2)  +  ei/r  (r  —p  —  1) (8). 

Now  multiply  (8)  by  e^  and  subtract  the  result  from  (6),  ob- 
serving that  by  (7)  we  have 

i/r  in)  —  e^'yjrin  —p)  =  ^  (n)  —  e^"*  <^  {n  —p  + 1) ; 

thus  we  obtain 

<f>  ir)  -  e^  ^  (r  -p)  =v^  -  eV 

+  v""''  e  {(p  {r  -p)  -  e^-'  <^  (r  -  2p  +  1)} 
+  v''-'e{<\>{r-p-\-l)  -e^"'^  (r-2^+2)} 
+ ...  ' 

j^e[^(r-r)-e"<t>{^-p)] (9). 

681.     The  equation  in  Finite  Differences  which  we  have  just 


CONDORCET.  365 

obtained  may  be  solved  in  the  ordinary  way ;  we  shall  not  how- 
ever proceed  with  it. 

One  case  of  interest  may  be  noticed.  Suppose  r  infinite ;  then 
fj)  (^r—p),  (/>  (r  —  2/?  +  1),  ...  will  all  be  equal.  Thus  we  can  obtain 
the  probability  that  the  event  will  happen  p  times  in  succession 
before  it  fails  p  times  in  succession  in  an  indefinite  number  of 
trials.     Let  F  denote  this  probability  ;  then  we  have  from  (9), 

-e^F(t;^-'+^;^-'+...  +  v  +  l). 
Hence  after  reduction  we  obtain 

F=    ^^-^g-o (10) 

682.  The  problems  which  we  have  thus  solved  are  solved  by 
Laplace,  Theorie...des  Proh.  pages  2^7 — 251.  In  the  solution 
we  have  given  we  have  followed  Condorcet's  guidance,  with  some 
deviations  however  which  we  will  now  indicate  ;  our  remarks  will 
serve  as  additional  evidence  of  the  obscurity  which  we  attribute 
to  Condorcet. 

Our  original  equation  (1)  is  given  by  Condorcet ;  his  demon- 
stration consists  merely  in  pointing  out  the  following  identity ; 

(v  +  ey  =  'if{v  +e)'^  +  v'-'e  {v  +  e)'^  +  v'^e  {v  +  e)"^^'  +  ... 
...+v''e{v  +  ey-^  +  ve  {v  +  e)'""'  +  e  (t;  +  e)^-\ 

He  arrives  at  an  equation  which  coincides  with  (4).  He  shews 
that  the  real  roots  must  be  numerically  greater  than  v ;  but  wdth 
respect  to  the  imaginary  roots  he  infers  that  the  moduli  cannot 
be  greater  than  unity,  because  if  they  were  </>  (r)  would  be  infinite 
when  T  is  infinite. 

We  may  add  that  Condorcet  shews  that  (4)  has  no  root  which 

is  a  simple  imaginary  quantity,  that  is  of  the  form  a  v  —  1. 

If  in  our  equation  (7)  we  substitute  successively  for  ^/r  in  t^rms 
of  <^  we  obtain 

-i/r  (r)  =  </)  (r)  -  e^"'  {0  [r  -^  +  1)  -  ec/)  [r  - p)] 

-  i'-^  [^  (r  -  2^  +  1)  -  ec/)  (r  -  2/?)} 

-  i^-^  {cf>  (r  -Sp  +  l)-e<l>  {r  -  Sp)} 


366  CONDOKCET. 

On  his  page  75  Condorcet  gives  an  equivalent  result  without 
explicitly  using  (7) ;  but  he  affords  very  little  help  in  establish- 
ing it. 

Let  X  (^')  tlenote  what  </>  (r)  becomes  when  v  and  e  are  inter- 
changed ;  that  is  let  %  (r)  denote  the  probability  that  in  r  trials 
the  event  will  fail^  times  in  succession  before  it  happens  ^  times 
in  succession. 

Let  E  denote  the  value  of  %  (r)  when  r  is  infinite.  Then  we 
can  deduce  the  value  of  E  from  that  of  V  by  interchanging  v  and 
e ;  and  we  shall  have  V+  E=  1,  as  we  might  anticipate  from  the 
result  at  the  end  of  Art.  679. 

Condorcet  says  that  we  shall  have 

where  f  is  une  fonction  semhlable  de  v  et  de  e. 

Thus  it  would  appear  that  he  had  some  way  of  arriving  at 
these  results  less  simple  than  that  which  we  have  employed ;  for 
in  our  way  we  assign  V  and  E  definitely. 

It  will  be  seen  that 

E  ~  e-'  l-v"' 

and  this  is  less  than  —  if  v  be  greater  than  e. 

We  have  then  two  results,  namely 

^_(£)_^  V    tf 

the  first  of  these  results  is  obvious  and  the  second  has  just  been 
demonstrated.     From  these  two  results  Condorcet  seems  to  draw 

the  inference  that       ,  ;  continually  diminishes  as  r  increases  ;  see 

his  page  78.     The  statement  thus  made  may  be  true  but  it  is  not 
demonstrated. 

Condorcet  says  on  his  page  78,  La  probabilite  en  general  que 
la  decision  sera  en  faveur  de  la  vcrite,  sera  exprimee  par 

^^  (1  -v)[l-  e") 
e"  (1  -e){l-  v^)  * 


CONDORCET.  367 

.  V 

This  is  not  tnie.     In  fact  Condorcet  gives  -p  for  the  probability 

when  he  ought  to  give  -^ — ^ ,  that  is  V. 

Condorcet  says  on  the  same  page,  Le  cas  le  plus  favorable  est 
celui  oil  Ton  aura  d'abord  j^  decisions  consecutives,  sans  aucun 
melange.  It  would  be  difficult  from  the  words  used  by  Condorcet 
to  determine  what  he  means ;  but  by  the  aid  of  some  s^^mbolical 
expressions  which  follow  we  can  restore  the  meaning.  Hitherto 
he  has  been  estimating  the  probability  before  the  trial  is  made ; 
but  he  now  takes  a  different  position  altogether.  Suppose  we  are 
told  that  a  question  has  been  submitted  to  a  series  of  tribunals,  and 
that  at  last  p  opinions  in  succession  on  the  same  side  have  been 
obtained ;  we  are  also  told  the  opinion  of  every  tribunal  to  which 
the  question  was  submitted,  and  we  wish  to  estimate  the  pro- 
bability that  the  decision  is  correct.  Condorcet  then  means  to 
say  that  the  highest  probability  will  be  when  the  first  ^  tribunals 
all  concuiTed  in  opinion. 

Condorcet  continues,  S'il  y  a  quelque  melange  dans  le  cas  de 

jo  =  2, il  est  clair  que  le  cas  le  plus  defavorable  sera  celui 

de  toutes  les  valeurs  paires  de  r,  oil  le  rapport  des  probabilites 

.    v^    e      V       ^   ^  •      ^1  • 

est  -3- .  -  =  - ,     Let  us  examine  tnis. 
eve 

Suppose  that  p  =  2.    Suppose  we  are  told  that  a  decision  has 

been  obtained  after  an  odd  number  of  trials  ;  then  we  estimate  the 

probability  of  the  correctness  of  the  decision  at  .  For  sup- 
pose, for  example,  that  there  were  five  trials.  The  probabilities  of  the 
correctness  and  of  the  incorrectness  of  the  decision  are  proportional 
respectively  to  evev^  and  veve"^,  that  is  to  v  and  e.  On  the  other 
hand,  suppose  we  are  told  that  the  decision  has  been  obtained  after 
an  even  number  of  trials ;  then  in  the  same  way  we  shall  find  that 
the  probabilities  of  the  correctness  and  of  the  incorrectness  of  the 
decision    are   proportional   respectively   to  v^   and  e^.     Thus   the 

.       .        v"  . 

probability  of  the  correctness  of  the  decision  is  -^ ^ ;  and  this 

V 

is  greater  than  ,  assuming  that  v  is  greater  than  e.     Thus 


368  CONDORCET. 

we  see  the  meaning  which  Condorcet  should  have  expressed,  and 
although  it  is  almost  superfluous  to  attempt  to  correct  what  is 
nearly  unintelligible,  it  would  seem  that  paires  should  be  changed 
to  impaires. 

683.  Condorcet's  problem  may  be  generalised.  We  may  ask 
what  is  the  probability  that  in  r  trials  the  event  will  happen 
p  times  in  succession  before  it  fails  q  times  in  succession.  In  this 
case  instead  of  (7)  we  shall  have 

'^{7i)  =  <i>  {n)  —  e^~^  [(f>  {n  —  g  -^  1)  —  e^lr  {n  -  q)] ; 
instead  of  (9)  we  shall  have 

(l){r)-'e^(j>{r-q)=v''{l-e') 

+  v""-'  e  {(/) (r -p)  -  e^"'  <f>  (r -p-q  +  l)\ 

+  V ^"' e  {(^  (r -^  +  1 )  - e«-'  (f>  {r -^- q+ 2)] 

+  ... 

and  instead  of  (10)  we  shall  have 

^^"  (1  -  e^ 

684.  We  will  introduce  here  two  remarks  relating  to  that 
part  of  Condorcet's  Preliminary  Discourse  which  bears  on  his 
ninth  Hypothesis. 

On  page  xxxvi.  he  says, 

...c'est  qu'en  supposant  que  I'on  connoisse  le  nombre  des  decisions 
et  la  pluralite  de  chacune,  on  pent  avoir  la  somme  des  pluralites  obte- 
nues  contre  I'opinion  qui  I'emporte,  plus  graiide  que  celle  des  pluralites 
conformes  a  cet  avis. 

This  is  a  specimen  of  a  kind  of  illogical  expression  which  is 
not  uncommon  in  Condorcet.  He  seems  to  imply  that  the  result 
depends  on  our  knoiving  something,  whereas  the  result  might 
happen  quite  independently  of  our  knowledge.  If  he  will  begin 
his  sentence  as  he  does,  his  conclusion  ought  to  be  that  we  may 
have  a  certain  result  and  know  that  lue  have  it. 

On  page  xxxvii.  he  alludes  to  a  case  which  is  not  discussed 
in  the  Essay.     Suppose  that  a  question  is  submitted  to  a  series 


CONDORCET.  369 

of  tribunals  until  a  certain  number  of  opinions  in  succession  on 
the  same  side  has  been  obtained,  the  opinions  of  those  tribunals 
being  disregarded  in  which  a  sj^ecified  plurality  did  not  concur. 
Let  V  be  the  probability  of  an  opinion  for  one  alternative  of  the 
question,  "svhich  we  will  call  the  affirmative;  let  e  be  the  proba- 
bility of  an  opinion  for  the  negative ;  and  let  z  be  the  j)robability 
that  the  opinion  will  have  to  be  disregarded  for  want  of  the  re- 
quisite plurality.  Thus  v  +  e  +  z  =  1.  Let  r  be  the  number  of 
ojDinions  on  the  same  side  required,  q  the  number  of  tribunals. 
Suppose  (v-}-zy  to  be  expanded,  and  let  all  the  terms  be  taken 
between  v^  and  v*"  both  inclusive ;  denote  the  aggTegate  by  0  (v). 
Let  (f>  (e)  be  formed  from  (f>  (v)  by  putting  e  for  v.  Then  (/>  {v)  is 
the  i^i'obability  that  there  will  be  a  decision  in  the  affirmative, 
and  (f>  {e)  is  the  jDrobability  that  there  will  be  a  decision  in  the 
negative.  But,  as  we  have  said,  Condorcet  does  not  discuss  the 
case. 

685.  Hitherto  Condorcet  has  always  supposed  that  each  voter 
had  only  two  alternatives  presented  to  him,  that  is  the  voter  had 
a  proposition  and  its  contradictory  to  choose  between ;  Condorcet 
now  proposes  to  consider  cases  in  which  more  than  two  proj)o- 
sitions  are  submitted  to  the  voters.  He  saj^s  on  his  page  86  that 
there  will  be  three  Hy23otheses  to  examine ;  but  he  really  arranges 
the  rest  of  this  j^art  of  his  Essay  under  tiuo  H}qDotheses,  namely  the 
tenth  on  pages  86 — 94?,  and  the  eleventh  on  pages  95 — 136. 

686.  Condorcet's  tenth  Hypothesis  is  thus  given  on  his 
page  XLII : 

...celle  oil  Ton  suppose  que  les  Yotans  peuvent  non-seulement  voter 
pour  ou  centre  une  proposition,  mais  aussi  declarer  qu'ils  ne  se  croient 
pas  assez  instruits  pour  prononcer. 

The  pages  89 — 94?  seem  even  more  than  commonly  obscure. 

687.  On  his  page  94<  Condorcet  begins  his  eleventh  H}-]30- 
thesis.  Suppose  that  there  are  6^  +  1  voters  and  that  there  are 
three  propositions,  one  or  other  of  which  each  voter  affirms.  Let 
V,  e,  i  denote  the  probabilities  that  each  voter  will  affirm  these 
three  propositions  respectively,  so  that  ?;  +  e  +  /=l.  Condorcet 
indicates  various  problems  for  consideration.  We  may  for  example 
suppose  that  three  persons  A,  B,  C  are  candidates  for  an  office, 

24 


370  CONDORCET. 

and  that  v,  e,  i  are  the  probabiHties  that  a  voter  will  vote  for  A,  B,  C 
respectively.  Since  there  are  6^+1  voters  the  three  candidates 
cannot  be  bracketed,  but  any  two  of  them  may  be  bracketed.  We 
may  consider  three  problems. 

I.  Find  the  probability  that  neither  B  nor  C  stands  singly  at 
the  head. 

II.  Find  the  probability  that  neither  B  nor  C  is  hefore  A, 

III.  Find  the  probability  that  A  stands  singly  at  the  head. 

These  three  probabilities  are  in  descending  order  of  magnitude. 
In  III.  we  have  all  the  cases  in  which  A  decisively  beats  his  two 
opponents.  In  II.  we  have,  in  addition  to  the  cases  in  III.,  those 
in  which  A  is  bracketed  with  one  opponent  and  beats  the  other. 
In  I.  we  have,  in  addition  to  the  cases  in  II.,  those  in  which  A  is 
beaten  by  both  his  opponents,  who  are  themselves  bracketed,  so 
that  neither  of  the  two  beats  the  other. 

Suppose  for  example  that  q  =  l.  We  may  expand  {v  +  e  +  iy 
and  pick  out  the  terms  which  will  constitute  the  solution  of  each 
of  our  problems. 

For  III.  we  shall  have 

v'  +  7v'  {e  +  i)  +  21v'  (e  +  if  +  85y*  (e  +  if  +  ^ov'  ^ii\ 

For  II.  we  shall  have  in  addition  to  these 

For  I.  we  shaJl  have  in  addition  to  the  terms  in  II. 

7v  1^eH\ 

These  three  problems  Condorcet  briefly  considers.  He  denotes 
the  probabilities  respectively  by  IF ^  TF/,  and  W"^.  It  will  scarcely 
be  believed  that  he  immediately  proceeds  to  a  fourth  problem  in 
which  he  denotes  the  probability  by  TF/^,  which  is  nothing  hut  the 
second  problem  over  again.  Such  however  is  the  fact.  His  enun- 
ciations appear  to  be  so  obscure  as  even  to  have  misled  himself 
But  it  will  be  seen  on  examination  that  his  second  and  fourth 
problems  are  identical,  and  the  final  expressions  which  he  gives 
for  the  probabilities  agree,  after  allowing  for  some  misprints. 


COXDORCET.  371 

688.  It  may  be  interesting  to  give  Cordorcet's  own  enun- 
ciations. 

I.  ...soit  TF^  la  probabilite  que  ni  e  ni  i  n'obtiendront  sur  les  deux 
autres  opinions  la  pluralite, . . .     page  95. 

II.  ...  W/  exprimant  la  probabilite  que  e  et  i  n'ont  pas  sur  v  la 
pluralite  exigee,  sans  qu'il  soit  necessaire,  pour  rejeter  un  terme,  que 
I'un  des  deux  ait  cette  pluralite  sur  I'autre,...     page  100. 

III.  . . .  TF'^,  c'est-a-dire,  la  probabilite  que  v  obtiendra  sur  i  et  e  la 
pluralite  exigee, . . .     page  1 02. 

lY.  ...TF/^,  c'est-a-dire,  la  probabilite  que  v  surpassera  un  des 
deux  i  ou  e,  et  pourra  cependant  etre  egal  a  I'autre,...    page  102. 

Of  these  enunciations  I.,  III.,  and  TV.  present  no  difficulty; 
II.  is  obscure  in  itself  and  is  rendered  more  so  by  the  fact  that 
we  naturally  suppose  at  first  that  it  ought  not  to  mean  the  same 
as  IV.  But,  as  we  have  said,  the  same  meaning  is  to  be  given 
to  II.  as  to  lY. 

Before  Condorcet  takes  these  problems  individually  he  thus 
states  them  together  on  his  page  95 : 

...nous  chercherons  la  probabilite  joour  un  nombre  donne  de  Yotans, 
ou  que  ni  e  uii  ne  I'emportent  sur  v  d'une  i^luralite  exigee,  ou  que  e  et  i 
I'emportent  chacun  sur  v  de  cette  pluralite  sans  I'emporter  Tun  sur 
I'autre,  ou  enfin  que  v  I'emporte  a  la  fois  sur  e  et  sur  i  de  cette  pluralite. 

Thus  he  seems  to  contemplate  three  problems.  The  last  clause 
ow  enfin  ...  pluralite  gives  the  enunciation  of  the  third  problem 
distinctly.  The  clause  ou  que  ni  . . .  exigee  may  perhaps  be  taken 
as  the  enunciation  of  the  second  problem.  The  clause  ou  que  ... 
Vautre  will  then  be  the  enunciation  of  the  first  problem. 

In  the  Preliminary  Discourse  the  problems  are  stated  together 
in  the  following  words  on  page  XLIV : 

...qu'on  cherche...ou  la  probabilite  d'ayoir  la  pluralite  d'un  avis  sur 
les  deux,...,  ou  la  probabilite  que,  soit  les  deux  autres,  soit  un  seul  des 
deux,  n' auront  pas  la  pluralite  ;... 

In  these  words  the  problems  are  enunciated  in  the  order 
III.,  IL,  I. ;  and  knowing  what  the  problems  are  we  can  see  that 
the  words  are  not  inapplicable.  But  if  we  had  no  other  way  of 
testing  the  meaning  we  might  have  felt  uncertain  as  to  what 

problems  II.  and  I.  were  to  be. 

24—2 


872  CONDORCET. 

689.  Condorcet  does  not  discuss  these  problems  with  much 
detail.  He  gives  some  general  considerations  with  the  view  of 
shewing  how  what  he  denotes  by  W^^^  may  be  derived  from  TV^; 
but  he  does  not  definitely  work  out  his  suggestions. 

We  will  here  establish  some  results  w^hich  hold  when  the 
number  of  voters  is  infinite. 

We  wdll  first  shew  that  when  q  is  infinite  W/  is  equal  to  unity, 
provided  that  v  is  greater  than  either  e  or  i  Suppose  {v  +  e+iY^'^^ 
expanded  in  the  form 

{v  +  6)^^^  +  {6q  +  l){v  +  er  i  +  ^t^-^  (^  ^.  ey 

16^41 
'  4^  +  1    zg'  ^         ' 


\Gq-l    '2 


^^  + 


Now  take  the  last  term  which  we  have  here  explicitly  given, 
and  pick  out  from  it  the  part  which  it  contributes  to  W^. 

We  have  {v  +  e)*^"^^  =  {v  +  eY'"-'   -f-  +  -—  , 

Expand  \ 1 \       as  far  as  the  term  which  involves 

f    V   \^^^^  f   V  e    \ 

,  and  denote  the  sum  by  /  ,  J .     Then  finally 


the  part  which  we  have  to  pick  out  is 

\6q±l 


+  ey 


(V               6     \ 
,  )  is  equal  to 

unity  when  q  is  infinite,  as  we  have  already  shewn ;  see  Art.  660. 

Hence  we  see  that  when  q  is  infinite  the  value  of  W/  is  the 
limit  of 

{v  +  e)^^^  +  {6q  +  l){v  +  6)^  I  +  ^^^  ^  ^J  ^^  {v  +  e)*^-^  i'  + 

16(7  +  1 

Now  we  are  at  liberty  to  suppose  that  { is  not  greater  than  e, 
and  then  i?4-6  is  greater  than  2i;  so  that  v-\-e  must  be  greater 


CONDORCET.  373 

2 

than  ^.     Hence  by  Art.  67^  the  value  of  W/  will  be  unity  when 

q  is  infinite. 

Let  </)  (v,  ei)  stand  for  W^,  where  we  mean  by  our  notation  to 
draw  attention  to  the  fact  that  TF/  is  a  symmetrical  function  of  e 
and  ^.     We  have  then  the  following  result  strictly  true, 

(j>  {v,  ei)  +  (j)  {e,  vi)  +  <j>  {i,  ev)  —  1. 

Now  suppose  q  infinite.  Let  v  be  greater  than  e  or  /;  then  as 
we  have  just  shewn  0  {v,  ei)  =  1,  and  therefore  each  of  the  other 
functions  in  the  above  equation  is  zero.  Thus,  in  fact,  </>  {x,  yz) 
vanishes  if  x  be  less  than  y  07^  z,  and  is  equal  to  unity  if  x  be 
greater  than  hotli  y  and  z. 

Next  suppose  v  —  e,  and  i  less  than  v  or  e.  By  what  we  have 
just  seen  0  (/,  ev)  vanishes ;  and  (/>  (v,  ei)  =  c^  {e,  vi),  so  that  each 

of  them  is  ^  . 

Lastly,  suppose  that  v  —  e  —  i.     Then 

<^  [Vy  ei)  =  0  (e,  vi)  =  <f>  [i,  ev)  ; 

hence  each  of  them  is  ^ . 

o 

We  may  readily  admit  that  wlien  q  is  infinite  W^  and  W"^ 
are  each  equal  to  TF/ ;  thus  the  results  which  we  have  obtained 
with  respect  to  Problem  li.  of  Art.  687  will  also  apply  to  Problems 
I.  and  III. 

Condorcet  gives  these  results,  though  not  clearly.  He  estab- 
lishes them  for  W^  without  using  the  fundamental  equation  we 
have  used.  He  says  the  same  values  will  be  obtained  by  examining 
the  formula  for  TT/^.  He  proceeds  thus  on  his  page  10^  :  Si 
maintenant  nous  cherchons  la  valeur  de  TT^  nous  trouverons  que 
TF*  est  ^gal  a  I'unite  moins  la  somme  des  valours  de  TF'*,  on  Ton 
auroit  mis  v  pour  e,  et  reciproquement  v  pour  i,  et  reciproquement. 
The  words  after  TF'*  are  not  intelligible;  but  it  would  seem  that 
Condorcet  has  in  view  such  a  fundamental  equation  as  that  we 
have  used,  put  in  the  form 

(/)  {v,  ei)  =  1  —  <^  (e,  vi)  —  (j>  {i,  ev). 

But  such  an  equation  will  not  be  true  except  on  the  assumption 


374)  CONDORCET. 

that  W'^  and  W"^  are  equal  toTf/  ultimately;  and  on  this  assump- 
tion we  have  the  required  results  at  once  without  the  five  lines 
which  Condorcet  gives  after  the  sentence  we  have  just  quoted. 

690.  In  the  course  of  his  eleventh  Hypothesis  Condorcet 
examines  the  propriety  of  the  ordinary  mode  of  electing  a  person 
by  votes  out  of  three  or  more  candidates.  Take  the^  following 
example ;  see  his  page  LViil. 

Suppose  A,  B,  C  are  the  candidates ;  and  that  out  of  60  votes 
23  are  given  for  A,  19  for  B,  and  18  for  C.  Then  A  is  elected 
according  to  ordinary  method. 

But  Condorcet  says  that  this  is  not  necessarily  satisfactory.  For 
suppose  that  the  23  who  voted  for  A  would  all  consider  C  better 
than  B  ;  and  suppose  that  the  19  who  voted  for  B  would  all  con- 
eider  (7  better  than  A  ;  and  suppose  that  of  the  18  who  voted  for 
C,  16  would  prefer  B  to  A,  and  2  would  prefer  A  to  B.  Then  on 
the  whole  Condorcet  gets  the  following  result. 

The  two  propositions  in  favour  of  C  are  C  is  better  than  A, 
C  is  better  than  B. 

The  first  of  these  has  a  majority  of  87  to  23,  and  the  second 
a  majority  of  41  to  19. 

The  two  propositions  in  favour  of  B  are  B  is  better  than  A, 
B  is  better  than  G. 

The  first  of  these  has  a  majority  of  35  to  25,  the  second  is 
in  a  minority  of  19  to  41. 

The  two  propositions  in  favour  of  A  are  A  is  better  than  B, 
A  is  better  than  C. 

The  first  of  these  is  in  a  minority  of  25  to  35,  and  the  second 
in  a  minority  of  23  to  37. 

Hence  Condorcet  concludes  that  G  who  was  lowest  on  the 
poll  in  the  ordinary  way,  really  has  the  greatest  testimony  in  his 
favour ;  and  that  A  who  was  highest  on  the  poll  in  the  ordinary 
way,  really  has  the  least. 

Condorcet  himself  shews  that  his  own  method,  which  has  just 
been  illustrated,  will  lead  to  difficulties  sometimes.  Suppose,  for 
example,  that  there  are  23  voters  for  A,  19  for  B,  and  18  for  G. 
Suppose  moreover  that  ah  the  23  who  voted  for  A  would  have 
preferred  B  to  G;   and  that  of  the  19  who  voted   for  By  there 


COXDORCET.  375 

are  17  who  prefer  C  to  A,  and  2  who  prefer  A  to  C;  and  lastly 
that  of  the  18  who  voted  for  C  there  are  10  who  prefer  A  to  B, 
and  8  who  jDrefer  B  to  A.  Then  on  the  whole,  the  following  three 
projDositions  are  affirmed: 

B  is  better  than  (7,  by  42  votes  to  18  ; 

G  is  better  than  A,  by  35  votes  to  25  ; 

A  is  better  than  B,  by  38  votes  to  27. 

Unfortunately  these  propositions  are  not  consistent  with  each 
other. 

Condorcet  treats  this  subject  of  electing  out  of  more  than 
two  candidates  at  great  length,  both  in  the  Essay  and  in  the 
Preliminary  Discourse  ;  and  it  is  resumed  in  the  fifth  part  of 
his  Essay  after  the  ample  cUscussion  which  it  had  received  in  the 
first  part.  His  results  however  appear  of  too  little  value  to  detain 
us  any  longer.     See  Laplace,  Theorie  . . .  des  Proh.  page  27i. 

691.  The  general  conclusions  which  Condorcet  draws  from 
the  first  part  of  his  work  do  not  seem  to  be  of  great  importance  ; 
they  amount  to  little  more  than  the  very  obvious  principle  that 
the  voters  must  be  enlightened  men  in  order  to  ensure  our  con- 
fidence in  their  decision.     We  will  quote  his  own  words  : 

On  voit  done  ici  que  la  forme  la  plus  propre  a  remphr  toutes  les 
conditions  exigees,  est  en  nieme  temps  la  plus  simple,  celle  ou  une 
assemblee  unique,  composee  d'hommes  eclaires,  prononce  seule  un  juge- 
ment  a  une  pluralite  telle,  qu'on  ait  une  assui'ance  suffisante  de  la 
verite  du  jugement,  meme  lorsque  la  pluralite  est  la  moindre,  et  il  faut 
de  plus  que  le  nombre  des  Yotans  soit  assez  grand  pour  avok  une  grande 
probabihte  d'obtenir  une  decision. 

Des  Votans  eclaires  et  une  forme  simple,  sent  les  moyens  de  reunir 
le  plus  d'avantages.  Les  formes  compliquees  ne  remedient  point  au 
defant  de  lumieres  dans  les  Yotans,  ou  n'y  remedient  qu'imparfaitement, 
ou  meme  entrainent  des  inconveniens  plus  grands  que  ceux  qu'on  a 
vouhi  eviter.     Page  XLii. 

...  11  faut,  1°  dans  le  cas  des  decisions  sur  des  questions  compliquees, 
faire  en  sorte  qne  le  systeme  des  propositions  simples  qui  les  forment 
soit  rigoureusement  developpe,  que  chaque  avis  possible  soit  bien  expose, 
que  la  voix  de  chaque  Yotant  soit  prise  sur  chacune  des  propositions  qui 
forment  cet  avis,  et  non  sur  le  resultat  seul 


37G  CONDORCET. 

2°.  II  faiit  de  plus  que  les  Yotans  soient  eclaires,  et  d'autant  plus 
eclaires,  que  les  questions  qu'ils  decident  sont  plus  compliquees ;  sans 
cela  on  trouvera  bien  ime  forme  de  decision  qui  preservera  de  la  crainte 
d'une  decision  fausse,  mais  qui  en  meme  temps  rendant  toute  decision 
presque  impossible,  ne  sera  qu'un  moyen  de  perpetuer  les  abus  et  les 
mauvaises  loix.     Page  lxix. 

692.  We  now  come  to  Condorcet's  second  part,  which  occupies 
his  pcages  137 — 175.  In  the  first  part  the  following  three  elements 
were  always  supposed  known,  the  number  of  voters,  the  hypothesis 
of  plurality,  and  the  probability  of  the  correctness  of  each  voter's 
vote.  From  these  three  elements  various  results  were  deduced, 
the  i^rincipal  results  being  the  probability  that  the  decision  will 
be  correct,  and  the  probability  that  it  will  not  be  incorrect ;  these 
probabilities  were  denoted  by  (j>  {q)  and  1— 'v/r(^)  in  Art.  669. 
Now  in  his  second  part  Condorcet  supposes  that  we  know  only  huo 
of  the  three  elements,  and  that  we  know  one  of  the  two  results ; 
from  these  known  quantities  he  deduces  the  remaining  element 
and  the  other  result;  this  statement  applies  to  all  the  cases 
discussed  in  the  second  part,  except  to  two.  In  those  two  cases 
we  are  supposed  to  know  the  probability  of  the  correctness  of  a 
decision  which  we  know  has  been  given  with  the  least  admissible 
plurality ;  and  in  one  of  these  cases  we  know  also  the  probability 
of  the  correctness  of  each  voter  s  vote,  and  in  the  other  case  the 
hypothesis  of  plurality. 

Condorcet  himself  has  given  three  statements  as  to  the  con- 
tents of  his  second  part ;  namely  on  pages  xxil,  2,  and  187;  of 
these  only  the  first  is  accurate. 

693.  Before  proceeding  to  the  main  design  of  his  second  part 
Condorcet  adverts  to  two  subjects. 

First  he  notices  and  condemns  Buffon's  doctrine  of  moral  cer- 
tainty ;  see  Condorcet's  pages  LXXi  and  138.  One  of  his  objections 
is  thus  stated  on  page  138  : 

Cette  opinion  est  inexacte  en  elle-meme,  en  ce  qu'elle  tend  a  con- 
fondre  deux  clioses  de  nature  essentiellement  differente,  la  probabilite  et 
la  certitude  :  c'est  precisement  comme  si  on  confondoit  I'asymptote 
d'une  courbe  avec  ime  tangente  menee  a  un  point  fort  eloigne  ;  de  telles 
suppositions  ne  pourroient  etre  admises  dans  les  Sciences  exactes  sans  en 
detruire  toute  la  precision. 


CONDORCET.  377 

Without  undertaking  the  defence  of  BufFon  we  may  remark 
that  the  illustration  given  by  Condorcet  is  not  fortunate ;  for  the 
student  of  Geometry  knows  that  it  is  highly  important  and  useful 
in  many  cases  to  regard  an  asymptote  as  a  tangent  at  a  very  re- 
mote point. 

Secondly,  Condorcet  adverts  to  the  subject  of  Mathematical 
Expectation;  see  his  pages  LXXV  and  142.  He  intimates  that 
Daniel  Bernoulli  had  first  pointed  out  the  inconveniences  of  the 
ordinary  rule  and  had  tried  to  remedy  them,  and  that  D'Alembert 
had  afterwards  attacked  the  rule  itself;  see  Arts.  378,  4G9,  471. 

694.  The  second  part  of  Condorcet's  Essay  presents  nothing 
remarkable;  the  formuloe  of  the  first  part  are  now  employed  again, 
with  an  interchange  of  given  and  sought  quantities.  Methods  of 
approximating  to  the  values  of  certain  series  occupy  pages  155 — 171. 
Condorcet  quotes  from  Euler  what  we  now  call  Stirling's  theorem 
for   the  ajDproximate  calculation  of  \x ;  Condorcet  also  uses  the 

formula,  due  to  Lagrange,  which  we  now  usually  express  symboli- 
cally thus 

AX=(e'^-l)X- 
See  also  Lacroix,  Traite  du  Cole.  Diff. ...  Vol.  iii.  jDage  92. 

Condorcet's  investigations  in  these  approximations  are  dis- 
figured and  obscured  by  numerous  misprints.  The  method  which 
he  gives  on  his  pages  168,  169  for  successive  approximation  to  a 
required  numerical  result  seems  unintelligible. 

695.  We  now  arrive  at  Condorcet's  third  part  which  occupies 
his  pages  176 — 241.     Condorcet  says  on  his  page  176, 

Nous  avons  suffisammeiit  expose  Tobjet  ole  cette  troisieme  Partie  :  on 
a  vu  qu'elle  devoit  renfermer  I'examen  de  deux  questions  differentes. 
Dans  la  premiere,  il  s'agit  de  conuoitre,  d'apres  I'observatiou,  la  proba- 
bilite  des  jugemens  d'uii  Tribunal  ou  de  la  voix  de  chaque  Votant ;  dans 
la  seconde,  il  s'agit  de  determiner  le  degre  de  probabilite  necessaire  ])0\\v 
qu'on  puisse  agir  dans  differentes  circonstances,  soit  avec  prudence,  soit 
avec  justice. 

Mais  il  est  aise  de  voir  que  I'examen  de  ces  deux  questions  demaude 
d'abord  qu'on  ait  etabli  en  general  les  j^rincipes  d'apres  lesquels  on  peut 
determiner  la  probabilite  d'un  ^venement  futur  ou  inconnu,  nou  par  la 


378  CONDORCET. 

connoissance  dii  nombre  des  combinaisons  possibles  que  donnent  cet 
eveuement,  ou  revenement  oppose,  mais  seulement  par  la  connoissance 
de  I'ordre  des  evenemens  connus  ou  passes  de  la  meme  espece.  C'est 
I'objet  des  problemes  suivans. 

696.  Condorcet  devotes  his  pages  176 — 212  to  thirteen  pre- 
liminary problems,  and  then  his  pages  213 — 241  to  the  application 
of  the  problems  to  the  main  purposes  of  his  Essay. 

With  respect  to  these  preliminary  problems  Condorcet  makes 
the  following  historical  remark  on  his  page  LXXXIII, 

L'idee  de  cherclier  la  probabilite  des  evenemens  futurs  d'apres  la  loi 
des  evenemens  passes,  paroit  s'etre  presentee  a  Jacques  Bernoulli  et  a 
Moivre,  mais  ils  n'ont  donne  dans  leurs  ouvrages  aucune  metliode  pour 
y  parvenir. 

M".  Bayes  et  Price  en  ont  donne  una  dans  les  Transactions  philo- 
sophiques,  annees  1764  et  1765,  et  M.  de  la  Place  est  le  premier  qui  ait 
traite  cette  question  d'une  maniere  analytique. 

697.  Condorcet's  first  problem  is  thus  enunciated  : 

Soient  deux  evenemens  seuls  possibles  A  et  N,  dont  on  ignore  la 
probabilite,  et  qu'on  sache  seulement  que  A  est  arrive  m  fois,  et  N^ 
n  fois.  On  suppose  I'un  des  deux  Evenemens  arrives,  et  on  demande  la 
probabiUte  que  c'est  I'evenement  A,  ou  que  c'est  I'evenement  N,  dans 
riiy]^)othese  que  la  probabilite  de  chacun  des  deux  evenemens  est  con- 
stamment  la  meme. 

We  have  already  spoken  of  this  problem  in  connexion  with 
Bayes,  see  Art.  551. 

Condorcet  solves  the  problem  briefly.  He  obtains  the  ordinary 
result  that  the  probability  in  favour  of  A  is, 

f  x"^-"'  (1  -  xy  dx 


[  a:'"  (1  -  xY  dx 
J  ft 


0 


Wl  -|-  1 

and  this  is  equal  to ^r .    Similarly  the  probability  in  favour 

^  m  +  ?i  -h  2  J         1  J 

^j  .        n-\-\ 
of  N  IS 


m  +  ?i+  2* 

It  will  of  course  be  observed  that  it  is  only  by  w\ay  of  abbrevia- 
tion that  we  can  speak  of  these  results  as  deduced  from  the  hypo- 
thesis that  the  probability  of  the  two  events  is  constantly  the 


CONDORCET.  879 

same ;  the  real  hypothesis  involves  much  more,  namely,  that  the 
probability  is  of  unknown  value,  any  value  between  zero  and  unity 
being  equally  likely  a  priori. 

Similarly  we  have  the  following  result.  Suppose  the  event  A 
has  occurred  m  times  and  the  event  N  has  occurred  n  times ;  sup- 
pose that  the  probability  of  the  two  events  is  constantly  the  same, 
but  of  unknown  value,  any  value  between  a  and  h  being  equally 
likely  a  priori ;  required  the  probability  that  the  probability  of  A 
lies  between  certain  limits  a  and  ^  which  are  themselves  com- 
prised between  a  and  h. 

The  required  probability  is 


i 


'  x'^il-xYdx 


f 

J  a 


x"^  (1  -  xy  dx 

a 

Laplace  sometimes  speaks  of  such  a  result  as  the  jyrohahilitii 
that  the  p)Ossihilitij  oi  A  lies  between  a  and /3 ;  see  Theorie...des 
Proh.  Livre  ii.  Chapitre  vi.  See  also  De  Morgan,  Theory  of  Proba- 
bilities, in  the  Encyclopcedia  Metropolitana,  Art.  77,  and  Essay  on 
Probahilities  in  the  Cabinet  Cyclopedia,  page  87. 

698.     Condorcet's  second  problem  is  thus  enunciated : 

On  suj^pose  dans  ce  Problem e,  que  la  probabilite  de  A  et  de  N  n'est 
pas  la  meine  dans  tous  les  evenemens,  mais  qu'elle  pent  avoir  pour 
chacun  une  valeur  quelconque  depuis  zero  jusqu'a  I'unite. 

Condorcet's  solution  depends  essentially  on  this  statement.  The 
probability  of  m  occurrences  of  A,  and  n  occurrences  of  N  is 

\m-\-n  (  r^        ) "'  f  f ^  ] "  \m-\-n     \ 

.      I      \     xdx  \    \\   {1-x)  dx\  ,  that  is  '.      ,      -^^^i^Tn  • 
\]]}[^   [Jo        )     Ih  J  lull!}.  ^ 

The  probability  of  having  A  again,  after  A  has  occurred  m  times 

and  N  has  occurred  n  times,  is  found  by  changing  the  exponent  m 

into  m  +  1,  so  that  it  is 

\m  +  n     1 

Proceeding  in  this  way  Condorcet  finally  arrives  at  the  conclu- 
sion that  the  probability  of  having  A  is  ^  and  the  probability  of 


380  CONDOHCET. 

Laving  iV  is  ^ .     In  fact  the  hypothesis  leads  to  the  same  conclu- 

sion  as  we  should  obtain  from  the  hypothesis  that  A  and  N  are 
always  equally  likely  to  occur. 

In  his  first  problem  Condorcet  assumes  that  the  probability  of 
each  event  remains  constant  during  the  observations  ;  in  his  second 
problem  he  says  that  he  does  not  assume  this.  But  we  must 
observe  that  to  abstain  from  assuming  that  an  element  is  constant 
is  different  from  distinctly  assuming  that  it  is  not  constant.  Con- 
dorcet, as  we  shall  see,  seems  to  confound  these  two  things.  His 
second  problem  does  not  exclude  the  case  of  a  constant  probability, 
for  as  we  have  remarked  it  is  coincident  with  the  case  in  which 

there  is  a  constant  probability  equal  to  ^  . 

The  introduction  of  this  second  problem,  and  of  others  similar 
to  it  is  peculiar  to  Condorcet.  We  shall  immediately  see  an  appli- 
cation which  he  makes  of  the  novelty  in  his  third  problem  ;  and  we 
shall  not  be  able  to  commend  it. 

699.     Condorcet's  third  problem  is  thus  enunciated  : 

On  suppose  dans  ce  probleme  que  Ton  ignore  si  a  chaque  fois  la  pro- 
bahilite  d' avoir  A  qvl  N  reste  la  meme,  on  si  elle  varie  a  chaque  fois,  de 
nianiere  quelle  puisse  avoir  une  valeur  quelconque  depuis  zero  jusqu'a 
r  unite,  et  Ton  demande,  sacliant  que  Ton  a  eu  m  evenemens  -4,  et  n 
evenemens  N^  quelle  est  la  probabilite  d'amener  A  ou  -^V. 

The  following  is   Condorcet's  solution.     If  the  probability  is 

constant,  then  the  probability  of  obtaining  m  occurrences  of  A 

I  m  -\-  n    r^ 
and    71    occurrences    of  N    is    ',      ,   -      x"'  (1  —  xY  dx,     that    is 

If  the  probability  is  not  constant,  then,  as  in 


\m  \n    \m-\-7i  +  l 


the  second  problem,  the  probability  of  obtaining  7n  occurrences  of  ^ 

I  !ii  -\-n     \ 
and  n  occurrences  of  N  is  ^r^^rr^ .     Hence  he  infers  that  the 

P  Q 

probabilities  of  the  hypothesis  are  respectively  and   ^     , 

\m\n  1 

where  P= — — —  ^   and   Q  = 


m-]-n  +  l  2 


m+n 


CONDORCET.  381 

He  continues  in  the  usual  way.     If  the  first  hypothesis  be  true 

tn  -j- 1 

the  probability  of  another  A  is ;  if  the  second  hypo- 

^  "^  771  +  W  +  2  ^^ 

thesis  be  true  the  probability  of  another  ^  is  ^ .     Thus  finally  the 
probability  in  favour  of  A  is 

P+  (3  V^  +  ^  +  2     ^2  ^J- 
Similarly  the  probability  in  favour  of  N  is 

1        f      ?2  +  1 


-^p^\q\ 


It  should  be  noticed  that  in  this  solution  it  is  assumed  that 
the  two  hypotheses  were  equally  probable  d  yrioriy  which  is  a  very 
important  assumption. 

700.  Suppose  that  m  +  n  is  indefinitely  large  ;  if  m  =  n  it  may 
be  shewn  that  the  ratio  of  P  to  Q  is  indefinitely  small ;  this  ratio 
obviously  increases  as  the  difference  of  m  and  n  increases,  and  is 
indefinitely  large  when  m  or  n  vanishes.  Condorcet  enunciates 
a  more  general  result,  namely  this ;  if  we  suppose  m  =  an  and 
n  infinite,  the  ratio  of  P  to  Q  is  zero  if  a  is  unity,  and  infinite 
if  a  is  greater  or  less  than  unity.     Condorcet  then  proceeds, 

Ainsi  supposons  m  et  n  donnes  et  inegaiix  ;  si  on  continue  d' observer 
les  evenemens,  et  que  m  et  n  conservent  la  meme  proportion,  on  parvi- 
endra  a  une  valeur  de  m  et  de  n,  telle  qu'on  aura  une  probabilite  anssi 
grande  qu'on  voudra,  que  la  probabilite  des  evenemens  A  et  J^  est  con- 
stante. 

Par  la  meme  raison,  lorsque  m  et  n  sont  fort  grands,  leur  difference, 
quoique  tres-grande  en  elle-meme,  pent  etre  assez  petite  par  rapport  au 
nornbre  total,  pour  que  Ton  ait  une  tres-grande  probabilite  que  la  pro- 
babilite d'avoir  A  ou  iV^n'est  pas  constante. 

The  second  paragi^aph  seems  quite  untenable.  If  in  a  very 
large  number  of  trials  A  and  N  had  occurred  very  nearly  the  same 
number  of  times  we  should  infer  that  there  is  a  constant  proba- 
bility namely  ^  for  A  and  ^  for  N.     It  is  the  more  necessary  to 


382  CONDORCET. 

record  dissent  because  Condorcet  seems  to  attach  great  importance 
to  his  third  problem,  and  the  inferences  he  draws  from  it ;  see  his 
pages  Lxxxiv,  xcii,  221. 

701.  Condorcet's  fourth  problem  is  thus  enunciated  : 

On  suppose  ici  un  evenement  A  arrive  m  fois,  et  tin  evenement  N 
arrive  oi  fois ;  que  Ton  sache  que  la  probabilite  inconnue  d'un  des  eve- 

nemens  soit  depuis  1  jusqu'a  ^,  et  celle  de  1' autre  depuis  ;;r  jusqu'a  zero, 

et  Ton  demande,  dans  les  trois  hypotheses  des  trois  problemes  precedens, 

P.  la  probabilite  que  c'est  A  ou  iVdont  la  probabilite  est  depuis  1  jusqu'a  ^; 

2°.  la  probabilite  d'avoir  A  ou  iV  dans  le  cas  d'un  nouvel  evenement ; 
3".  la  probabilite  d'avoir  un  evenement  dont  la  probabilite  soit  depuis 

1  jusqu'a  ^ . 

Condorcet  uses  a  very  repulsive  notation,  namely, 

The  chief  point  in  the  solution  of  this  problem  is  the  fact  to 
which  we  have  drawn  attention  in  the  latter  part  of  Art.  G97. 

We  may  remark  that  Condorcet  begins  his  solution  of  the 
second  part  of  his  problem  thus  :  Soit  supposee  maintenant  la  pro- 
babilite changeante  a  chaque  evenement.  He  ought  to  say,  let  the 
probability  not  be  assumed  constant.     See  Art.  698. 

702.  Condorcet's  fifth  problem  is  thus  enunciated  : 

Conservant  les  memes  hypotheses,  on  demande  quelle  est,  dans  le  cas 
du  probleme  premier,  la  probabilite,  1°.  que  celle  de  I'evenement  A  n'est 
pas  au-dessous  d'une  quantite  donnee  j  2°.  qu'elle  ne  dilBfere  de  la  valeur 

moyenne   que  d'une  quantite  a  ;  3°.  que  la  probabilite  d'amener  A, 

n'est  point  au-dessous  d'une  limite  a ;  4".  qu'elle  ne  differe  de  la  pro- 
babilite   moyenne     ^    que  d'une  quantite  moindre  que  a.     On 

demande  aussi,  ces  probabilites  etant  donnces,  quelle  est  la  limite  a 
pour  laquelle  elles  ont  lieu. 

The  whole  solution  depends  on  the  fact  to  which  we  have 
drawn  attention  in  the  latter  part  of  Art.  697. 


CONDOBCET.  383 

As  is  very  common  with  Condorcet,  it  would  be  uncertain  from 
his  language  what  questions  he  proposed  to  consider.  On  examin- 
ing his  solution  it  appears  that  his  1  and  3  are  absolutely  identical, 
and  that  his  2  and  4  differ  only  in  notation. 

703.  In  his  sixth  problem  Condorcet  says  that  he  proposes  the 
same  questions  as  in  his  fifth  problem,  taking  now  the  hypothesis 
that  the  probability  is  not  constant. 

Here  his  1  and  3  are  really  different,  and  his  2  and  4  are  really 
different. 

It  seems  to  me  that  no  value  can  be  attributed  to  the  discus- 
sions which  constitute  the  problems  from  the  second  to  the  sixth 
inclusive  of  this  part  of  Condorcet's  work.  See  also  Cournot's 
Exposition  de  la  Theorie  cles  Chances... -psige  166. 

704.  The  seventh  problem  is  an  extension  of  the  first.  Sup- 
pose there  are  two  events  A  and  N,  which  are  mutually  exclusive, 
and  that  in  m  +  n  trials  A  has  happened  m  times,  and  N  has  hap- 
pened n  times :  required  the  probability  that  in  the  next  p  +q 
trials  A  will  happen  j;  times  and  N  happen  q  times. 

Suppose  that  x  and  1  —  x  were  the  chances  of  A  and  JSf  s.t  a 
single  trial ;  then  the  probability  that  in  m  +  n  trials  A  would 
happen  m  times  and  iV^  happen  n  times  would  be  proportional  to 
x"'  (1  —  xy.  Hence,  by  the  rule  for  estimating  the  probabilities  of 
causes  from  effects,  the  probability  that  the  chance  of  A  lies  be- 
tween X  and  x  +  dx  at  a  single  trial  is 

x'^Q.-xydx 

{  r»'"  (1  -  xf  dx         y 

J  0 

And  if  the  chance  of  ^  at  a  single  trial  is  x  the  probability 
that  mp-\-q  trials  A  will  occur  j)  times  and  N  occur  q  times  is 

^===-x'{\-xy. 
^^  ,     . 

Hence  finally  the  probability  required  in  the  problem  is 

,      ,  ^   \  x"^-"' il  -  xY^'' dx 
\P±±K 

\e[i    fx^'{i-xydx 


384^  CONDORCET. 

This  important  result  had  been  given  in  effect  by  Laplace  in 
the  memoir  which  we  have  cited  in  Art.  551 ;  but  in  Laplace's  me- 
moir we  must  suppose  the  ^-?  +  </  events  to  be  required  to  happen 

\P  -^  ^  . 
in  an  assiqned  order,  as  the  factor   , — :'     is  omitted. 

We  shall  see  hereafter  in  examining  a  memoir  by  Prevost 
and  Lhuilier  that  an  equivalent  result  may  also  be  obtained  by  an 
elementary  algebraical  process. 

705.  The  remaining  problems  consist  chiefly  of  deductions 
from  the  seventh,  the  deductions  being  themselves  similar  to  the 
problems  treated  in  Condorcet's  first  part.  We  will  briefly  illus- 
trate this  by  one  example.  Suppose  tliat  A  has  occurred  m  times 
and  B  has  occurred  n  times ;  required  the  probability  that  in  the 
next  2q  +  l  trials  there  will  be  a  majority  in  favour  of  A.  Let 
F{q)  denote  this  probability  ;   then 

[  x'''  (1  -  xY  cj,  (q)  dx 

ic'"  (1  -  xY  dx 

^  0 

where  <^  (q)  stands  for 

x'^-"'  +  {2q  +  1)  x''  {l-x)  +  ^^^  +  1^^^^  x'^-'  (1  -  xy+ 

\2q+l 
~==r  X'^'  (1  -  xy. 


...+ 


Hence  if  we  use,  as  in  Art.  663,  a  similar  notation  for  the  case 
in  which  q  is  changed  into  q  +  1,  we  have 

[  x'''{l-xy^(q  +  l)dx 

x'""  (1  -  xy  dx 

•^  0 

Therefore,  as  in  Art.  663, 

Cx'^l-xyU{q+l)~cl>{q)\dx 

F(q+1)-F(q)=i^ ^.r-^ ^ , 

x'''{i-xydx 

J  n 


CONDORCET.  385 

where  i>  (g  + 1)  -  4>  iq)  ^  I^TT^  I""'"  ^^  ~  "''^'"  ~  '"'*'  ^^  -^)'' j  • 

In  this  manner  Condorcet  deduces  various  formulae  similar  to 
equation  (2)  of  Art.  663. 

We  may  remark  that  at  first  Condorcet  does  not  seem  to  deduce 
his  formulae  in  the  simplest  way,  namely  by  applying  the  results 
which  he  has  already  obtained  in  his  first  part ;  but  he  does 
eventually  adopt  this  plan.     Compare  his  pages  191  and  208. 

706.  Condorcet  now  proceeds  to  the  ai^plication  of  the  problems 
to  the  main  purposes  of  his  Essay.  As  he  says  in  the  passage  we 
have  quoted  in  Art.  695,  there  are  two  questions  to  be  considered. 
The  first  question  is  considered  in  pages  213 — 223,  and  the  second 
question  in  pages  223 — 241. 

707.  The  first  question  asks  for  two  results  ;  Condorcet  barely 
notices  the  first,  but  gives  all  his  attention  to  the  second. 

Condorcet  proposes  two  methods  of  treatment  for  the  first  ques- 
tion ;  the  premier  moyen  is  in  pages  213 — 220,  and  the  seconde 
methode  in  pages  220 — 223.  Neither  method  is  carried  out  to  a 
practical  application. 

708.  We  will  give  a  simple  illustration  of  what  Condorcet  pro- 
poses in  his  first  method.  Suppose  we  have  a  tribunal  composed 
of  a  large  number  of  truly  enlightened  men,  and  that  this  tribunal 
examines  a  large  number  of  decisions  of  an  inferior  tribunal.  Sup- 
pose too  that  we  have  confidence  that  these  truly  enlightened  men 
will  be  absolutely  correct  in  their  estimate  of  the  decisions  of  the 
inferior  tribunal.  Then  we  may  accept  from  their  examination 
the  result  that  on  the  whole  the  inferior  tribunal  has  recorded  m 
votes  for  truth  and  n  votes  for  error.  We  are  now  ready  to  apjDly 
the  problem  in  Art.  704,  and  thus  determine  the  probability  that 
out  of  the  next  2q  +  l  votes  given  by  members  of  the  inferior  tri- 
bunal there  will  be  a  majority  in  favour  of  the  truth. 

This  must  be  taken  however  only  as  a  very  simple  case  of  the 
method  proposed  by  Condorcet ;  he  himself  introduces  circum- 
stances which  render  the  method  much  more  complex.  For  in- 
stance he  has  not  complete  confidence  even  in  his  truly  enlightened 

25 


386  CONDORCET. 

men,  but  takes  into  account  the  probability  that  they  will  err  in 
their  estimate  of  the  decisions  of  the  inferior  tribunal.  But  there 
would  be  no  advantage  gained  in  giving  a  fuller  investigation  of 
Condorcet's  method,  especially  as  Condorcet  seems  to  intimate  on 
his  page  216  that  the  following  is  the  chief  result : 

...ce  qui  conduit  en  general  a  cette  conclusion  tres-importante,  que 
tout  Tribunal  dont  les  jugemens  sont  rendus  a  une  petite  pluralite, 
relativement  au  nombre  total  des  Yotans,  doit  inspirer  peu  de  confiance, 
et  que  ses  decisions  n'ont  qu'une  tres-petite  probabilite. 

Such  an  obvious  result  requires  no  elaborate  calculation  to 
support  it. 

709.  In  the  second  method  of  treating  the  first  question  Con- 
dorcet does  not  suppose  any  tribunal  composed  of  truly  enlightened 
men  to  review  the  decisions  of  those  who  are  less  enlightened. 

But  he  assumes  that  the  probability  of  the  correctness  of  each  vote 

1 
lies  between  ^  and  1 ;  and  then  he  proposes  to  apply  some  of  the 

formulse  which  he  obtained  in  the  solutions  of  the  preliminary 
problems.  Nothing  of  any  practical  value  can  be  extracted  from 
this  part  of  the  book.     Condorcet  himself  says  on  his  page  c, 

II  auroit  6te  curieux  de  faire  a  la  suite  des  decisions  de  quelque 
Tribunal  existant,  I'application  de  ce  dernier  principe,  mais  il  ne  nous 
a  ete  possible  de  nous  procurer  les  donnees  necessaires  pour  cette  appli- 
cation. D'ailleurs  les  calculs  auroient  et6  tres-longs,  et  la  necessite 
d'en  supprimer  les  resultats,  s'ils  avoient  et6  trop  defavorables,  n'etoit 
pas  propre  a  donner  le  courage  de  s'y  livrer. 

710.  Condorcet  now  proceeds  to  the  second  question  which  we 
have  seen  in  Art.  695  that  he  proposed  to  consider,  namely  the 
numerical  value  of  the  probability  which  ought  to  be  obtained 
in  various  cases.  This  occupies  pages  223 — 21^1  of  the  Essay ; 
the  corresponding  part  of  the  Preliminary  Discourse  occupies 
pages  cii — c XXVIII.  This  discussion  is  interesting,  but  not  of 
much  practical  value.  Condorcet  notices  an  opinion  enunciated 
by  Buffon.  Buffon  says  that  out  of  10,000  persons  one  will  die  in 
the  course  of  a  day ;  but  practically  the  chance  of  dying  in  the 


CONDORCET.  387 

course  of  a  day  is  disregarded  by  mankind ;  so  that  may 

be  considered  tbe  numerical  estimate  of  a  risk  which  any  person  is 
willing  to  neglect.  Condorcet  objects  to  this  on  various  grounds  ; 
and  himself  proposes  a  different  numerical  estimate.  He  finds 
from  tables  of  mortality  that  the  risk  for  a  person  aged  37  of  a 

sudden  death  in  the  course  of  a  week  is  -r-^ — zttt^  ,  and  that  the 

o2  X  o80 

risk  for  a  person  aged  47  is  — — j^ .  He  assumes  that  prac- 
tically no  person  distinguishes  between  these  risks,  so  that  their 
difference  is  in  fact  disregarded.     The  difference  between  these 

fractions  is  TTi>fw^,  and  this  Condorcet  proposes  to  take  as  a  risk 

which  a  man  would  practically  consider  equivalent  to  zero  in  the 
case  of  his  own  life.     See  Art.  644. 

711.  Condorcet  considers  however  that  the  risk  which  we 
may  with  propriety  neglect  will  vary  with  the  subject  to  which  it 
relates.  He  specially  considers  three  subjects,  the  establishment 
of  a  new  law,  the  decision  between  claimants  as  to  the  right  to  a 
property,  and  the  condemnation  of  an  accused  person  to  capital 
punishment.  We  may  observe  that  he  records  the  opinion  that 
capital  punishments  ought  to  be  abolished,  on  the  ground  that, 
however  large  may  be  the  probability  of  the  correctness  of  a 
single  decision,  we  cannot  escape  having  a  large  probability  that  in 
the  course  of  many  decisions  some  innocent  person  will  be  con- 
demned.    See  his  pages  cxxvi,  241. 

712.  We  now  arrive  at  Condorcet's  fourth  part,  which  occupies 
pages  242 — 278.     He  says  on  his  page  242, 

Jusqu'ici  nous  n'avons  considere  notre  sujet  que  d'une  maniere  ab- 
straite,  et  les  suppositions  generales  que  nous  avons  faites  s'eloignent 
trop  de  la  rialite.  Cette  Partie  est  destinee  h  developper  la  methode  de 
faire  entrer  dans  le  calcul  les  principales  donnees  auxquelles  on  doit 
avoir  egard  pour  que  les  resultats  oil  Ton  est  conduit,  soient  applicables 
a  la  pratique. 

Condorcet  divides  this  part  into  six  questions.     In  these  ques- 

25—2 


388  CONDORCET. 

tions  he  proposes  to  examine  the  modifications  which  the  results  of 
the  preceding  parts  of  his  book  require,  before  they  can  be  applied 
to  practice.  For  instance  we  cannot  in  practice  suppose  it  true 
that  all  the  voters  are  of  equal  skill  and  honesty ;  and  accordingly 
one  of  the  six  questions  relates  to  this  circumstance. 

But  the  subjects  proposed  for  investigation  are  too  vague  to  be 
reduced  with  advantage  to  mathematical  calculation ;  and  ac- 
cordingly we  find  that  Condorcet's  researches  fall  far  below  what 
his  enunciations  appear  to  promise.  For  example,  on  page  264, 
he  says, 

Nous  examinerons  ici  I'influence  qui  peut  resulter  de  la  passion  ou 
de  la  mauvaise  foi  des  Yotans. 

These  words  may  stimulate  our  curiosity  and  excite  our  atten- 
tion ;  but  we  are  quite  disappointed  when  we  read  the  paragraph 
which  immediately  follows : 

Comme  la  probahilite  n'a  pu  etre  determinee  que  par  I'experience, 
si  I'on  suit  la  premiere  methode  de  la  troisieme  Fartie,  ou  qu'en  sui- 
vant  la  seconde,  ou  suppose  que  rinfluence  de  ]a  corruption  ou  de  la 
passion  sur  les  jugemens  ne  fait  pas  tomber  la  probahilite  au-dessous  de 

- ,  alors  il  est  evident  que  cet  element  est  entre  dans  le  calcul,  et  qu'il 

n'y  a  par  consequent  rien  a  corriger. 

Condorcet  himself  admits  that  he  has  here  effected  very  little ; 
he  says  on  his  page  CLiv, 

Ainsi  Ton  doit  regarder  sur-tout  cette  quatrieme  Partie  comme  un 
simple  essai,  dans  lequel  on  ne  trouvera  ni  les  developpemens  ni  les 
details  que  rimportance  du  sujet  pouri-oit  exiger. 

713.  Condorcet  himself  seems  to  attach  great  importance  to 
his  fifth  question  which  relates  to  that  system  of  forced  unanimity 
which  is  established  for  English  juries.  This  question  he  dis- 
cusses in  his  pages  267 — 276  and  CXL — CLi.  He  believes  that  he 
shews  that  the  system  is  bad.  He  introduces  the  subject  thus  on 
page  CXL : 

Les  jugemens  criminels  en  Angleterre  se  rendent  sous  cette  forme  : 
on  oblige  les  Jures  de  rester  dans  le  lieu  d'assemblee  jusqu'a  ce  qu'ils 
soient  d'accord,  et  on  les  oblige  de  se  reunir  par  cette  espece  de  torture ; 
car  non-seulement   la  faim  seroit  un  tourment  reel,    mais   I'ennui,  la 


CONDORCET.  389 

contrainte,  le  mal-aise,  portes  a  un  certain  point,  peuvent  devenir  un 
veritable  siipplice. 

Aiissi  poun'oit-on  faire  a  cette  forme  de  decision  un  reproclie  sem- 
blable  a  celui  qii'on  faisoit,  avec  tant  de  justice,  a  I'usage  barbare  et 
inutile  de  la  torture,  et  dire  qu'elle  donne  de  I'avantage  a  un  Jure 
robuste  et  fripon,  sur  le  Jure  integre,  mais  foible. 

He  says  that  there  is  a  class  of  questions  to  which  this  method 
of  forced  unanimity  cannot  he  applied ;  for  example,  the  truths  of 
Physical  Science,  or  such  as  depend  on  reasoning.  He  says  on 
page  CXLI, 

Aussi,  du  moins  dans  des  pays  ou  des  siecles  eclaires,  n'a-t-on  jamais 
exige  cette  unanimite  pour  les  questions  dont  la  solution  depend  du 
raisonnement.  Personne  n'hesite  k  recevoir  comme  une  verite  1' opinion 
unanime  des  gens  instruits,  lorsque  cette  unanimite  a  ete  le  produit 
lent  des  reflexions,  du  temps  et  des  recherches  :  mais  si  Ton  enfermoit 
les  vingt  plus  habiles  Pliysiciens  de  1' Europe  jusqu'a  ce  qu'ils  fussent 
convenus  d'un  point  de  doctrine,  personne  ne  seroit  tente  d'avoir  la 
moindre  confiance  en  cette  espece  d'unanimite. 

714'.  We  shall  not  reproduce  Condorcet's  investigations  on  the 
English  jury  S3^stem,  as  they  do  not  seem  to  us  of  any  practical 
value.  They  can  be  easily  read  by  a  student  who  is  interested  in 
the  subject,  for  they  form  an  independent  piece  of  reasoning,  and 
thus  do  not  enforce  a  perusal  of  the  rest  of  the  book. 

We  will  make  a  few  remarks  for  the  use  of  a  student  who  con- 
sults this  part  of  Condorcet's  book;  these  will  occupy  our  next 
Article. 

715.  On  page  CXLI  Condorcet  says  that  we  ought  to  dis- 
tinguish three  sorts  of  questions,  and  he  at  once  states  the  first ; 
as  usual  with  him  he  is  not  careful  in  the  subsequent  pages  to  indi- 
cate the  second  and  third  of  these  questions.  The  second  is  that 
beginning  on  page  CXLII,  II  y  a  un  autre  genre  cT opinions....  The 
third  is  that  beginning  on  page  CLi,  On  pent  considerer  encore.... 

On  his  page  267  Condorcet  says. 

Si  Ton  prend  rhy]3othese  huitieme  de  la  premiere  Partie,  et  qu'en 
consequence  Ton  suppose  que  Ton  prendra  les  voix  jusqu'a  ce  que 
r  unanimite  se  soit  reuuie  pour  un  des  deux  avis,  nous  avons  vu  que  le 


390  CONDOECET. 

calcul  donnoit  la  meme  probabilite,  soit  que  cette  unanimite  ait  lieu 
immediatement,  soit  qu'elle  ne  se  forme  qu'apres  plusieurs  changemens 
d'avis,  soit  que  Ton  se  remiisse  a  la  majoritej  soit  que  Tavis  de  la 
minorite  finisse,  par  avoir  tous  les  suj0frages. 

We  quote  this  passage  in  order  to  draw  attention  to  a  practice  of 
which  Condorcet  is  very  fond,  and  which  causes  much  obscurity  in 
his  writings ;  the  practice  is  that  of  needlessly  varying  the  lan- 
guage. If  we  compare  the  words  soit  que  Ton  se  reimisse  a  la 
viajoy^ite  with  those  which  immediately  follow,  we  discover  such  a 
great  diversity  in  the  language  that  we  have  to  ascertain  whether 
there  is  a  corresponding  diversity  in  the  meaning  which  is  to  be 
conveyed.  We  shall  conclude  on  examination  that  there  is  no 
such  diversity  of  meaning,  and  we  consequently  pronounce  the 
diversity  of  language  to  be  very  mischievous,  as  it  only  serves  to 
arrest  and  perplex  the  student. 

It  would  be  well  in  this  paragraph  to  omit  all  the  words  soit 
que  Von... suffrages;  for  without  these  everything  is  fully  expressed 
which  Condorcet  had  obtained  in  his  first  part. 

We  would  indicate  the  first  eleven  lines  of  Condorcet's  page  270 
as  involving  so  much  that  is  arbitrary  as  to  render  all  the  conclu- 
sions depending  on  them  valueless.  We  are  not  prepared  to  offer 
more  reasonable  suppositions  than  those  of  Condorcet,  but  we 
think  that  if  these  are  the  best  which  can  be  found  it  will  be 
prudent  to  give  up  the  attempt  to  apply  mathematics  to  the 
question. 

We  may  remark  that  what  is  called  Trial  hy  Jury  would  more 
accurately  be  styled  Trial  hy  Judge  and  Jury.  Accordingly  a  most 
important  element  in  such  an  investigation  as  Condorcet  under- 
takes would  be  the  influence  which  the  Judge  exercises  over  the 
Jury ;  and  in  considering  this  element  we  must  remember  that 
the  probability  is  very  high  that  the  opinion  of  the  Judge  will  be 
correct,  on  account  of  his  ability  and  experience. 

716.  We  now  arrive  at  Condorcet's  fifth  part;  which  occupies 
the  remainder  of  his  book,  that  is,  pages  279 — 304.  Condorcet 
says  on  page  CLVii, 

L'objet  de  cette  derniere  Partie,  est  d'appliquer  a  quelques  exemples 
les  principes  que  nous  avons  developpcs.     II  auroit  6t^  I.  desirer  que 


CONDORCET.  891 

cette  application  eut  pu  etre  faite  d'apres  des  donnees  reelles,  mais  la 
difficulte  de  se  procurer  ces  donnees,  difficultes  qu'un  particulier  ne 
pouvoit  esperer  de  vaincre,  a  force  de  se  contenter  d'appliquer  les  prin- 
cipes  de  la  theorie  a  de  simples  liyjootlieses,  afin  de  montrer  du  moins 
la  marclie  que  pourroient  suivre  pour  cette  application  reelle  ceux  a  qui 
on  auroit  j)rocure  les  donnees  qui  doivent  en  etre  la  base. 

But  it  would  be  rather  more  correct  to  describe  this  part  as 
furnishing  some  additions  to  the  preceding  investigations  than  as 
giving  examples  of  them. 

Four  so-called  examples  are  discussed. 

717.  In  the  first  example  Condorcet  proposes  what  he  thinks 
would  be  a  good  form  of  tribunal  for  the  trial  of  civil  cases.  He 
suggests  a  court  of  25  judges,  to  decide  by  majority.  He  adds, 
however,  this  condition ;  suppose  the  case  tried  is  the  right  to  a 
certain  property,  then  if  the  majority  is  less  than  3  the  court 
should  award  compensation  to  the  claimant  against  whom  de- 
cision is  given. 

718.  In  the  second  example  Condorcet  proposes  what  he 
thinks  would  be  a  good  form  of  tribunal  for  the  trial  of  criminal 
cases.  He  suggests  a  court  of  80  judges,  in  which  a  majority  of  at 
least  8  is  to  be  required  to  condemn  an  accused  person. 

719.  The  third  example  relates  to  the  mode  of  electing  from 
a  number  of  candidates  to  an  ofiice.  This  example  is  really  a 
supplement  to  the  investigation  given  in  the  first  part  of  the  Essay. 
Condorcet  refers  to  the  memoir  on  the  subject  by  a  celebrated 
geometer,  and  records  his  own  dissent  from  that  geometer's  sug- 
gestions ;  the  geometer  alluded  to  is  Borda.     See  Art.  690. 

720.  The  fourth  example  relates  to  the  probability  of  the 
accuracy  of  the  decision  of  a  large  assembly  in  which  the  voters 
are  not  all  alike.  Condorcet  considers  the  case  in  which  the  num- 
ber of  voters  whose  probability  of  accuracy  is  x,  is  proportional  to 

\—x\  and  he  supposes  that  cc  lies  between  ^  and  1.      In  such  a 

case  the  mean  probability  is 


2  CONDORCET. 

I    (1  —  x)  xdx 
^  ^  

I    {1  —  x)  dx 

2 
which  is  ^  .     If  the  value  of  x  lies  between  a  and  1  the  mean  pro- 
o 

bability  is  found  in  the  same  way  to  be  • — ^ —  . 

This  example  is  interesting,  but  some  parts  of  the  investiga- 
tions connected  with  it  are  very  obscure. 

As  in  other  parts  of  his  book  Condorcet  draws  a  very  in- 
significant inference  from  his  difficult  investigations.  He  says, 
page  303, 

On  voit  done  combien  il  est  important,  non-seulement  que  les 
hommes  soient  eclaires,  mais  qu'en  meme  temps  tous  ceux  qui,  dans 
I'opinion  publique,  passent  pour  instruits  ou  liabiles,  soient  exempts  de 
prejuges.  Cette  deriiiere  condition  est  meme  la  plus  essentielle,  puisqu'il 
paroit  que  rien  ne  peut  remedier  aux  inconveniens  qu'elle  entraine. 

721.  Besides  the  Essai  Condorcet  wrote  a  long  memoir  on  the 
Theory  of  Probability,  which  consists  of  six  parts,  and  is  published 
in  the  volumes  of  the  Hist  de  V A  cad.... Paris,  for  the  years  1781, 
1782,  1783,  and  1784. 

The  first  and  second  parts  appear  in  the  volume  for  1781 ; 
they  occupy  pages  707 — 728.  The  dates  of  publication  of  the 
volumes  are  as  usual  later  than  the  dates  to  which  the  volumes 
belong ;  the  portion  of  the  memoir  which  appears  in  the  volume 
for  1781  is  said  to  have  been  read  on  August  4th,  1784. 

722.  The  first  part  of  the  memoir  is  entitled  Reflexions  sur  la 
regie  generate  qui  prescrit  de  prendre  pour  valeur  d'lm  evenement 
incertain,  la  prohahilite  de  cet  evenement,  multipliee  par  la  valeur  de 
Vevenement  en  lui-meme. 

Suppose  that  p  represents  the  probability  that  an  event  will 
happen,  and  that  if  the  event  happens  a  person  is  to  receive  a  sum 
of  money  denoted  by  a ;  then  the  general  rule  to  which  Condorcet 
refers  is  the  rule  which  estimates  the  person's  advantage  at  the 
sum  pa.  On  this  rule  Condorcet  makes  some  remarks ;  and  these 
remarks   arc   also   given   in    substance    in   the   Essai,   in   pages 


CONDORCET.  393 

142 — 147.  The  sum  of  the  remarks  is  this  ;  Condorcet  justifies  the 
rule  on  the  ground  that  it  will  lead  to  satisfactory  results  if  a  very 
large  number  of  trials  be  made.  Suppose  for  example  that  A  and 
B  are  playing  together,  and  that  -4's  chance  of  winning  a  single 
game  is  p,  and  5's  chance  is  q  :  then  the  rule  prescribes  that  if  -4's 
stake  be  denoted  by  hp,  then  ^'s  stake  must  be  hq.  Now  we 
know,  by  Bernoulli's  Theorem,  that  if  A  and  B  play  a  very  large 
number  of  games,  there  is  a  very  high  probability  that  the  number 
which  A  wins  will  bear  to  the  number  which  B  wins  a  ratio  ex- 
tremely near  to  the  ratio  oi p  to  q.  Thus  if  the  stakes  are  adjusted 
according  to  the  general  rule  there  is  a  very  high  probability  that 
A  and  B  are  on  terms  of  equality  as  to  their  prospects ;  if  any 
other  ratio  of  the  stakes  be  adopted  a  proportional  advantage  is 
given  to  one  of  the  players. 

There  can  be  no  doubt  that  this  view  of  the  ground  on  which 
the  rule  is  to  be  justified  is  correct. 

723.  Condorcet  adverts  to  the  Petersburg  Problem.  The 
nature  of  his  remarks  may  be  anticipated.  Suppose  that  p  in 
the  preceding  Article  is  extremely  small  and  q  very  nearly  equal  to 
unity.  Then  ^'s  stake  is  very  large  indeed  compared  with  ^'s. 
Hence  it  may  be  very  imprudent  for  B  to  play  with  A  on  such 
terms,  because  B  may  be  ruined  in  a  few  games.  Still  it  remains 
true  that  if  A  and  B  agree  to  continue  playing  through  a  very 
long  series  of  games  no  proportion  of  stakes  can  be  fair  except  that 
which  the  general  rule  assigns. 

724.  The  second  part  of  Condorcet's  memoir  is  entitled  Ap- 
plication de  r analyse  a  cette  question:  Determiner  la  probabilite 
quun  arrangement  regulier  est  Veffet  d'une  intention  de  le  pro- 
duire. 

This  question  is  analogous  to  one  discussed  by  Daniel  Ber- 
noulli, and  to  one  discussed  by  Michell ;  see  Arts.  395  and  618. 

Condorcet's  investigations  rest  on  such  arbitrary  hypotheses 
that  little  value  can  be  attached  to  them.  We  will  give  one 
specimen. 

Consider  the  following  two  series : 

1,  2,  3,  4,  5,  6,  7,  8,  9,  10. 

1,  3,  2,  1,  7,  13,  23,  44,  87,  167. 


39^  CONDORCET. 

In  the  first  series  each  term  is  equal  to  twice  the  preceding 
term  diminished  by  the  term  which  precedes  that ;  and  in  the 
second  series  each  term  is  the  sum  of  the  four  which  precede  it. 
Condorcet  says, 

II  est  clair  que  ces  deux  suites  sent  reguheres,  que  tout  Mathe- 
maticien  qui  les  examinera,  verra  qu'elles  sent  toutes  deux  assujetties 
a  une  loi ;  mais  il  est  sensible  en  meme  temps  que,  si  Ton  arrete  une  de 
ces  suites  au  sixieme  terme,  par  exemple,  on  sera  plutot  porte  a  regarder 
la  premiere,  comme  etant  reguliere,  que  la  seconde,  puisque  dans  la 
premiere  il  y  aura  quatre  termes  assujettis  a  une  loi,  tandis  qu'il  n'y  en 
a  que  deux  dans  la  seconde. 

Pour  evaluer  le  rapport  de  ces  deux  probabilites,  nous  supposerons 
que  ces  deux  suites  soient  continuees  a  I'infini.  Comme  alors  il  y  aura 
dans  toutes  les  deux  un  nombre  infini  de  termes  assujettis  a  la  loi,  nous 
supposerons  que  la  probabilite  seroit  egale;  mais  nous  ne  connoissons 
qu'un  certam  nombre  de  termes'  assujettis  a  cette  loi ;  nous  aurons 
done  les  probabilites  que  I'une  de  ces  suites  sera  reguliere  plutot  que 
I'autre,  egales  aux  probabilites  que  ces  suites  etant  continuees  ^  I'infini, 
•  resteront  assujetties  a  la  m^me  loi. 

Soit  done  pour  une  de  ces  suites  e  le  nombre  des  termes  assujettis 
a  une  loi,  et  e  le  nombre  correspondant  pour  une  autre  suite,  et  qu'on 
cberche  la  probabihte  que  pour  un  nombre  q  de  termes  suivans,  la  meme 
loi  continuera  d'etre  observee.     La  premiere  probabilite  sera  exprimee 

par =-,  la  seconde  par  -. -,  et  le  rapport  de  la  seconde  a  la 

^      e+^+1  ^       e+q+\  ^ 

{e'^\)(e  +  q+\) 

premiere  par  7 —^, — - — -f . 

^  ^        (e+ 1)  (e  +2'+ 1) 

1                                                                                 .         e'  + 1 
Soit  g  =  7j  >  et  e,  q'  des  nombres  finis,    ce   rapport  devient   r-  . 

Ainsi  dans  Texemple  precedent,  si  Ton  s'arrcte  au  sixieme  terme,  on  aura 

3 

e  =  4,  e'  =  2,  et  le  rapport  sera  - :  si  on  s'arrcte  au  dixieme,  on  aura 

7 
e  =  8,  e'  =  6,  et  le  rapport  sera  ^ . 

Si  Ton  suppose  que  e  et  d  sent  du  meme  ordre  que  g,  le  memo 
rapport  devient  ^^ ,    ^^ ,  et  si  on  suppose  e  =  g-  =  1,  il  sera  - 


ee  +eq  1  +  e 

We  will  make  some  remarks  on  this  investigation. 


CONDORCET.  395 

e  + 1     ' 
The  result,  that  the  first  probability  is  — ■ -^  and  the  second 

6  +  ^+1 
'  _i_  1 

is  -7 =- ,  is  we  presume  obtained  by  Bayes's  Theorem. 

After  supposing  that  q  is  infinite  it  is  perplexing  to  be  told 
that  e  =  q  =  l.  Condorcet  should  have  proceeded  thus.  Sup- 
pose e  =  q,  then 

ee  +  eq        2e'  2x       ,  e' 

—. = -.  = Y>^here  x=  -  . 

ee  +  eq     e  -\-  e       1  +  x  e 

The  followinsf   then  is  the  result  which   Condorcet   considers 

himself  to  have  obtained.     Let  us  suppose  we  have  observed  in 

a   certain  series  that  a  certain  law  holds  during  so  many  terms 

as  form  the  fraction  x  of  the  whole  series,  then  the  comparative 

2x 
probability  that  the  whole  series  is  subject  to  this  law  is  ^j . 

JL  ^p  JO 

It  is  however  obvious  that  this  result  has  been  obtained  by 
means  of  several  most  arbitrary  hypotheses. 

725.  The  remainder  of  this  part  of  Condorcet's  memoir  is  dif- 
ficult, but  the  meaning  can  be  discovered  by  patience.  There  is 
nothing  that  appears  self-contradictory  excej^t  perhaps  on  page  727. 
In  the  last  line  Condorcet  takes  for  the  limits  of  a  certain  integra- 
tion b  and  1  —  a  +  Z> ;  it  would  seem  that  the  latter  limit  should -be 
1  —  a,  for  otherwise  his  Article  vil.  is  only  a  repetition  of  his 
Article  VI. 

726.  The  third  part  of  Condorcet's  memoir  is  entitled  Svr 
devaluation  des  Droits  eventuels.  It  is  published  in  the  Hist,  cle 
V Acad.... Paris,  for  1782  ;  it  occupies  pages  674 — 691. 

This  part  commences  thus  : 

La  destruction  du  Goiivernement  feodal  a  laiss'e  snbsister  en  Europe 
un  grand  nomhre  de  droits  eventuels,  mais  on  pent  les  reduire  a  deux 
classes  principales  j  les  uns  se  payeut  lorsque  les  proprietes  viennent  a 
changer  par  vente,  les  autres  se  payent  aux  mutations  par  succession, 
soit  directe  ou  collaterale,  soit  collaterale  seulement. 

Condorcet  then  proposes  to  determine  the  sum  of  money  which 
should  be  paid  down  in  order  to  free  any  proj)erty  from  such  feudal 
rights  over  it. 


396  CONDORCET. 

727.  The  following  paragraph  appears  very  remarkable  when 
we  reflect  how  soon  the  expectations  it  contains  were  falsified  by 
the  French  Kevolution. 

Premier  Principe.  Nous  supposerons  d'ahord  que  I'ordre  sui^ant 
lequel  les  dernieres  mutations  se  sont  succedees,  sera  indefiniment  con- 
tinue. 

Le  motif  qui  nous  a  fait  adopter  ce  principe,  est  la  grande  proba- 
bility que  nous  avons  moins  de  grands  changemens,  nioins  de  grandes 
revolutions  a  attendre  pour  I'avenir,  qu'il  n'y  en  a  eu  dans  le  pass6 :  le 
progres  des  lumieres  en  tout  genre  et  dans  toutes  les  parties  de  I'Europe, 
I'esprit  de  moderation  et  de  paix  qui  y  regno,  I'espece  de  m6pris  ou  le 
Machiavelisnie  commence  a  tomber,  semblent  nous  assurer  que  les  guerres 
et  les  revolutions  deviendront  a  I'avenir  moins  frequentes  j  ainsi  le 
principe  que  nous  adoptons,  en  memo  temps  qu'il  rend  les  calculs  et  les 
observations  plus  faciles,  a  de  plus  I'avantage  d'etre  plus  exact. 

728.  The  memoir  is  neither  important  nor  interesting,  and  it 
is  disfigured  by  the  contradiction  and  obscurity  which  we  have 
noticed  in  Condorcet's  Essay.  Condorcet  says  that  he  will  begin  by 
examining  the  case  in  which  the  event  producing  the  right  neces- 
sarily happens  in  a  certain  length  of  time,  as  for  example,  when 
the  right  accrues  on  every  succession  to  the  property ;  and  then  he 
will  consider  the  case  in  which  the  event  does  not  necessarily  hap- 
pen, as,  for  example,  when  the  right  accrues  on  a  sale  of  the  pro- 
perty, or  on  a  particular  kind  of  succession.  He  then  gives  three 
methods  for  the  first  case,  and  in  direct  contradiction  to  what  he 
has  said,  it  will  be  found  that  only  his  first  method  applies  to  the 
case  in  which  the  event  producing  the  right  necessarily  happens. 

729.  We  will  give  the  results  of  the  second  of  Condorcet's 
methods,  though  not  in  his  manner. 

Let  us  suppose  for  simplicity  that  the  sum  to  be  paid  if 
the  event  happens  is  one  pound ;  let  c  represent  the  present  worth 
of  one  pound  due  at  the  end  of  a  year ;  let  x  be  the  probability 
that  the  event  will  happen  in  the  course  of  one  year.  Then  xc 
represents  the  value  of  that  part  of  the  right  which  arises  from  the 
first  year,  x(^  the  value  of  that  part  which  arises  from  the  second 
year,  xc^  the  value  of  that  part  which  arises  from  the  third  year, 
and  so  on.     Thus  the  value  of  the  whole  right  is 


CONDORCET.  397 


a?  (c  4-  c^  +  c'  +  . . .),  that  is  :j — 


xc 
c 


The  question  now  arises  what  is  the  value  of  xl     Suppose  that 
during  m  +  n  past  years  the  event  hapjoened  771  times  and  did  not 

7)1 

happen  n  times  ;  we  mio^ht  reasonably  take for  x,  so  that  the 

rr  >  O  -^771+71 

C  711/ 

whole  value  of  the  rio^ht  would  be  -z .     Condorcet  how- 

\  —  c  m-\-7i 

ever  prefers  to  employ  Bayes's  Theorem,  and  so  he  makes  the 

whole  value  of  the  risfht 


1 


. 


x'^ii-xy-^^^dx 

1  — c 


/, 


that  is 


x""'  (1  -  xy  dx 

m+ 1  c 


m  +  7i-\-  2  1  —  c  * 


Moreover  Condorcet  supposes  that  at  the  present  moment  the 
event  has  just  happened  on  which  the  right  depends,  so  that  he 
adds  unity  to  the  result  and  obtains  for  the  value  of  the  whole  right 

m  +  1         c 


1  + 


7Jl  +  71  -^  2    1  —  C  * 


730.  The  investigation  of  the  preceding  Article  goes  over  the 
same  ground  as  that  on  page  680  of  the  volume  which  contains  the 
memoir,  but  is  we  hope  more  intelligible.  We  proceed  to  make 
two  remarks. 

First.  It  is  clear  that  Condorcet  is  quite  wrong  in  giving  this 
method  as  applicable  to  the  first  case,  namely  that  in  which  the 
event  must  happen  in  a  certain  length  of  years.  The  method  is 
quite  inapplicable  to  such  an  example  as  he  mentions,  namely 
when  the  right  would  accrue  on  the  next  succession  to  the  property, 
that  is,  on  the  death  of  the  present  holder ;  for  the  probability  of 
such  an  event  would  not  be  constant  from  year  to  year  for  ever  as 
this  method  assumes.  The  method  would  be  applicable  to  the 
example  of  the  second  case  in  which  the  right  is  to  accrue  upon 
a  sale,  for  that  might  without  absurdity  be  supposed  as  likely  to 
happen  in  one  year  as  in  another  for  ever. 


398  CONDORCET. 

Secondly.  We  see  no  advantage  in  applying  Bayes's  Theorem. 
Condorcet  is  very  fond  of  it;  and  throughout  this  memoir  as  well 
as  in  his  other  writings  on  the  subject  indulges  to  excess  in  signs 
of  integration.  In  the  above  example  if  m  and  n  are  very  large 
numbers  no  practical  change  is  made  in  the  result  by  using  Bayes's 
Theorem ;  if  m  +  w  is  a  small  number  our  knowledge  of  the  past 
would  be  insufficient  to  justify  any  confidence  in  our  anticipations 
of  the  future. 

731.  From  what  we  have  said  it  may  be  expected  that  when 
Condorcet  comes  to  his  second  case  he  should  be  obscure,  and  this 
is  the  fact.  He  gives  on  his  page  685  the  modifications  which  his 
three  methods  now  require.  The  second  method  is  really  un- 
altered, for  we  merely  suppose  that  observation  gives  m  and  n  in- 
stead of  m  and  n.  The  modification  of  the  third  method  seems 
unsound ;  the  modification  of  the  first  method  is  divided  into  two 
parts,  of  which  only  the  former  appears  intelligible. 

But  we  leave  these  to  students  of  the  original  memoir. 

732.  We  may  add  that  on  pages  687 — 690  Condorcet  gives  an 
investigation  of  the  total  value  arising  from  two  different  rights. 
It  is  difficult  to  see  any  use  whatever  in  this  investigation,  as  the 
natural  method  would  be  to  calculate  each  separately.  Some  idea 
of  the  unpractical  character  of  the  result  may  be  gathered  from  the 
fact  that  we  have  to  calculate  a  fraction  the  numerator  and  deno- 
minator of  which  involve  n  +  n  +  7i'  +  n"  —  2  successive  integra- 
tions. This  complexity  arises  from  an  extravagant  extension  and 
abuse  of  Bayes's  Theorem. 

733.  The  fourth  part  of  Condorcet's  memoir  is  intitled  Re- 
flexions SUV  la  methode  de  determiner  la  Prohahilite  des  Mnemens 
futurs,  d'apres  I'  Observation  des  evenemens  passes.  The  fourth  and 
fifth  parts  appeared  in  the  Hist  de  V  A  cad....  Paris,  for  1783  ;  they 
occupy  pages  539 — 559.  This  volume  was  published  in  1786, 
that  is  after  Condorcet's  Fssai  which  is  referred  to  on  page  54?  1. 

734.  Suppose  that  in  m  -f  n  trials  an  event  has  happened  m 
times  and  failed  n  times  ;  required  the  probability  that  in  the  next 


CONDORCET.  399 

p  +  q  trials  it  will  happen  p  times  and  fail  q  times.     The  required 
probability  is 

j^  +  q  ff'*'{i-^r''i^ 

''  0 

as  we  have  already  remarked  in  Art.  704. 

Condorcet  quotes  this  result ;  he  thinks  however  that  better 
formulae  may  be  given,  and  he  proposes  two.  But  these  seem 
quite  arbitrary,  and  we  do  not  perceive  any  reason  for  preferrino- 
them  to  the  usual  formula.  We  will  indicate  these  formulae  pro- 
posed by  Condorcet. 

I.  Let  t  =  7n+  71  +  2)  +  2'  ^^^  P^"^ 

3?,  ~r  ^o   I  "^Q  ~r  •  •  •    I   '^t 

U  =    -^ 2 3 . 

t 

then  the  proposed  formula  is 

\p  +  q  j     • ' '  ^"'"^  (^  ~  ^^y^'  ^^1  ^^2  •  •  •  ^^t 
L^  Li      jj[..,u'^  (1  -  uy  dx^  dx^  .,.dx 

The  limits  of  each  integration  are  to  be  0  and  1. 

II.  Suppose  an  event  to  have  happened  n  times  in  succession, 
required  the  probability  that  it  will  hap|)en  p  times  more  in  suc- 
cession. 

_  X^  "p  Xr,    X^  -p  X^^  -f-  X^  3/j  ~t"  X^    i~  •  •  •     I    Xf^ 

XjQXi    U  ^—  X^  ;::  ;;;  •  t .  • 

^23  n 

let  V  be  an  expression  similar  to  u  but  extended  to  n  +^:>  factors ; 
then  Condorcet  proposes  for  the  required  probability  the  formula 

I    I    I   •  •  I     C/  U/tX'j   Cf/Xn   •  •  •    ^Xf^ip 

III  ...u  dx^  dx,^ . . .  dx^ 

The  limits  of  each  integration  are  to  be  0  and  1. 

Condorcet  proposes  some  other  formulae  for  certain  cases  ;  tliey 


400  CONDORCET. 

are  as  arbitrary  as  those  which  we  have  ah*eady  given,  and  not 
fully  intelligible  ;  see  his  pages  550 — 553. 

735.  The  fifth  part  of  Condorcet's  memoir  is  entitled  Sur  la 
prohahilite  desfaits  extraordinaires. 

Suppose  that  p  is  the  probability  of  an  event  in  itself;  let  t 
denote  the  probability  of  the  truth  of  a  certain  witness.  This  wit- 
ness asserts  that  the  event  has  taken  place ;  required  the  proba- 
bility that  the  event  did  take  place,  and  that  it  did  not.  The 
required  probabilities  are 

Pt  and        (1  -P)  (1  -  0 

jyt+{\-p){\-t)  "^    pt^(l-p][\-t)- 

Condorcet  gives  these  formulae  with  very  little  explanation. 

The  application  of  these  formulae  is  not  free  from  difficulty. 
Suppose  for  example  a  trustworthy  witness  asserts  that  one  ticket 
of  a  lottery  of  10000  tickets  was  drawn,  and  that  the  number  of 

the  ticket  drawn  was  297.     Here  if  we  put  p  =  we  obtain 

such  a  very  small  value  of  the  truth  of  the  witness's  statement  that 
we  lose  our  confidence  in  the  formula.  See  Laplace  Theorie...des 
Proh.  pages  446 — 451.  De  Morgan,  Cambridge  Philosophical 
Transactions,  Vol.  ix.  page  119. 

736.  Condorcet  makes  remarks  on  two  points,  namely  the 
mode  of  estimating  p  and  the  mode  of  estimating  t  He  recurs  to 
the  former  point  in  the  sixth  part  of  his  memoir,  and  we  shall  give 
an  extract  which  will  shew  the  view  he  advocated  in  his  fifth  part, 
and  the  view  which  he  advocated  in  his  sixth  part. 

With  respect  to  the  second  point  Condorcet's  chief  remark  is 
that  the  probability  of  a  witness  is  not  the  same  for  all  facts.  If 
we  estimate  it  at  u  for  a  simple  fact,  then  we  should  estimate  it  at 
v^  for  a  compound  fact  consisting  of  two  simple  facts,  and  so  on. 
One  witness  however  may  be  as  capable  of  observing  a  compound 
fact  consisting  of  two  or  more  simple  facts  as  another  is  of  observ- 
ing a  simple  fact. 

737.  The  sixth  part  of  Condorcet's  memoir  is  entitled  Appli- 


CONDOBCET.  401 

cation  des  joTincipes  de  Varticle  2^^^^^cede}it  a  quelqves  questions  de 
critique.  It  is  published  in  the  Hist,  de  I' Acad. ...  Paris  for  1784; 
it  occupies  pages  454 — 468. 

738.  In  this  part  Condorcet  begins  by  adverting  to  some 
remarks  which  he  had  made  in  his  fifth  part  as  to  the  mode  of 
estimating  the  value  of  what  we  denoted  by  ^  in  Article  735.  He 
savs, 

J'ai  observe  en  meme-temps  qu'il  ne  falloit  pas  dans  ce  cas  entendre, 
par  la  probabilite  propre  d'un  fait,  le  rap^Dort  du  nombre  des  combi- 
naisons  ou  il  a  lieu,  avec  le  nombre  total  des  combinaisons.  Par  ex- 
emple,  si  d'un  jeu  de  dix  cartes  on  en  a  tire  une,  et  qu'un  temoin  me 
dise  que  c'est  telle  carte  en  particulier,  la  probal)ilite  propre  de  ce  fait, 
qu'il  s'agit  de  comparer  avec  la  i^robabilite  qui  nait  du  temoignage,  n'est 

pas  la  probabilite  de  tirer  cette  carte,  qui  seroit  yr  j  iiiais  la  probabilite 

d'amener  cette  carte  plutot  que  telle  autre  carte  determinee  en  parti- 
culier;  et   comma  toutes  ces   probabilites   sont    egales,    la   probabilite 

propre  est  ici  -^  . 

Cette  distinction  etoit  necessaire,  et  elle  suffit  pour  expliquer  la 
contrariete  d' opinions  entre  deux  classes  de  philosophes.  Les  uns  ne 
peuvent  se  persuader  que  les  memes  temoignages  puissent  produire, 
pour  un  fait  extraordinaire,  une  probabilite  egale  a  celle  qu'ils  produi- 
sent  pour  un  fait  ordinaire;  et  que,  par  exemple,  si  je  crois  un  homme 
de  bon  sens  qui  me  dit  qu'une  femme  est  accoucliee  d'un  gargon,  je 
dusse  le  croire  egalement  s'il  me  disoit  qu'elle  est  accoucliee  de  douze. 

Les  autres  au  contraire  sont  convaincus  que  les  temoignages  conser- 
rent  toute  leur  force,  pour  les  faits  extraordinaires  et  tres-peu  proba- 
bles, et  ils  sont  frapp6s  de  cette  observation,  que  si  on  tire  une  loterie 
de  100000  billets,  et  qu'un  homme,  digne  de  foi,  dise  que  le  numero 
256,  par  exemple,  a  eu  le  premier  lot,  personne  ne  doutera  de  son  tem- 
oignage, quoiqu'il  y  ait  99999  a  parier  centre  1  que  cet  evenement 
n'est  pas  arrive. 

Or,  au  moyen  de  1' observation  precedente,  on  voit  que  dans  le  second 

cas  la  probabilite  propre  du  fait  etant  -^ ,  le  temoignage  conserve  toute 

sa  force,  au  lieu  que  dans  le  premier,  cette  probabilite  etant  tres-petite, 
reduit  presque  a  rien  celle  du  temoignage. 

J'ai  propose  ensuite  de  prendre,  pour  la  probabilite  propre  du  fait, 

2G 


-102  CONDOR  CET. 

le  rapport  clu  noinbre  de   combinaisons  qui  donnent  ce  fait,  ou  un  fait 
semblable  an  nombre  total  des  combinaisons. 

Ainsi,  par  exemj^le,  dans  le  cas  on  on  tire  une  carte  d'nn  jeu  de 
dix  cartes,  le  nombre  des  combinaisons  ou  Ton  tire  une  carte  determin6e 
quelconque  est  un ;  celui  des  combinaisons  ou  Ton  tire  une  autre  carte 

-a- 

determinee  est  aussi  un ;  done  ^^  exprimera  la  probabilite  propre. 

Si  on  me  dit  qu'on  a  tire  deux  fois  de  suite  la  meme  carte,  alors  on 
trouvera  qu'il  n'y  a  que  dix  combinaisons  qui  donnent  deux  fois  une  meme 
carte,  et  quatre-vingt-dix  qui  donnent  deux  cartes  difFerentes  :  la  proba- 
bilite projDre  du  fait  n'est  done  que  ~,  et  celle  du  temoignage  com- 
mence a  devenir  plus  foible. 

Mais  je  crois  devoir  abaudonner  cette  maniere  de  considerer  la 
question,  1"  parce  qu'elle  me  paroit  trop  bypotlietique ;  2'^  parce  que 
souvent  cette  comparaison  d'evenemens  semblables  seroit  difficile  a  faire, 
ou,  ce  qui  est  encore  pis,  ne  se  feroit  que  d'apres  des  suppositions  arbi- 
traires ;  3°  parce  qu'en  I'appliquant  a  des  exemples,  elle  conduit  a  des 
resultats  trop  eloignes  de  ceux  que  donneroit  la  raison  commune. 

J'en  ai  done  clierclie  une  autre,  et  il  m'a  paru  plus  exact  de 
prendre,  pour  probabilite  jDropre  d'un  evenement,  le  rapport  de  la 
probabilite  de  cet  evenement  prise  dans  le  sens  ordinaire,  avec  la  pro- 
babilite moyenne  de  tons  les  autres  evenemens. 

739.  Thus  we  see  that  Condorcet  abandons  the  suggestion 
which  he  made  in  the  fifth  part  of  his  memoir  and  offers  another. 
It  does  not  seem  that  the  new  suggestion  escapes  any  of  the  objec- 
tions which  Condorcet  himself  advances  ao^ainst  the  old  suofpfestion, 
as  will  appear  by  the  analysis  we  shall  now  give  of  Condorcet's 
examples. 

7-iO.  Suppose  there  are  ten  cards  and  it  is  asserted  that  a 
specified  card  has  been  drawn  tAvice  running;  we  proceed  to  estimate 
the  j^'^^ohahilite  projwe  of  the  event.  There  are  9  other  ways  in 
which  the  same  card  can  be  drawn  twice,  and  the  ordinary  proba- 

.       .      1 

bility  of  each  drawing  is  r-rr  ;  there  are  45  ways  in  which  two  dif- 
ferent cards  are  obtained  in  two  drawings,  and  the  ordinary  proba- 

2 
bility  of  each  drawing  is  zr^  •     Hence  the  mean  probability  of  all 

the  other  events  is 


CONDORCET.  403 

If  '2  11  99 

54r^Ioo  +  ^^10o|'^^^*^^5400- 

I-Ience  according  to  Condorcet's  own  words  the  lovohahilite  p^opre 

1  99  .54 

should  be  — — -  -h-     .      ,  that  is  — .     But  he  himself  says  that  the 

prohaUlite  projjve  is  —r^,  so  that  he  takes  ^-ttt  -^  \^'^^  +  tttt, 

lo3  100        [o400      lOOJ 

1  99 

and  not  — -r  -^  ^'. .. ,.  .     That  is,   as  is  so  frequently  the  case  with 
100      o400  ^         *^ 

Condorcet,  his  own  words  do  not  express  his  own  meaning. 

Again  sujDpose  that  there  are  ten  cards  and  it  is  asserted  that  a 
specified  card  has  been  drawn  thrice  running ;  we  proceed  to  esti- 
mate the  prohahilite  propre  of  the  event.  Here  the  mean  proba- 
bility of  all  the  other  events  is 

6        ^^        3  9    )      ,    ,  .      999 


120  X  ~~  +  90  X  — -r  +  ——A  ,  that  is 


219  Y  ^  ^  1000  1000  ^  lOOOJ  '  219000  ' 

219 

Condorcet  says  that  the  jyrohabilite  propre  is  ,  so  that  he 

1         I    999  1    \     ■ 

1000  •   1219000  "^  lOOOJ  • 

741.     Condorcet  now  proceeds  to  apply  these  results  in  the 
following  words : 

Ainsi  siipposons,  par  exemple,  que  la  probabilite  du  temoignage  soit 

99 
r— -,  c'est-a-dire,   que  le  temoin   ne   se  trompe  ou  ne  veuille  tromper 

qu'une  fois  sur  cent,   on  aura,  d'apres  son  temoignage,  la  probabilite 

99  9900       ,         \.  .  .     1^.        •   ^      1  T    T.-rf'   ^^^^ 

IT— ^  OU  qu  on  a  tire  une  carte  determmee ;  la  probabilite 

^    ....  ,    9540 
qu'on  a  tire  deux  fois  la  meme  carte ;    et  la  probabilite  n-Q7rQ?|  <1^^  on 

I'a  tiree  trois  fois. 

We  find  some  difficulties  in  these  numbers. 
Let  p  denote  the  prohahilite  propre  and  t  the  probability  of 
the  testimony ;  then  the  formula  to  be  applied  is,  we  presume, 

^ In  the  first  case  it   seems   that    Condorcet 

i^^+(i-p)(i-0' 

26—2 


40  i  CONDORCET. 

supposes  p  =  1,  that  is  lie  takes  apparently  the  j^rohahilite  j^'i^ojwe 
to  be  177:  -=-  TT  -^  9  X  r-r  k  which  agrees  indeed  with  his  own  ivords 

but  not  with  his  practice  which  we  have  exhibited  in  Art.  740  ;  if 

1 

we  follow  that  practice  we  shall  have  P  =  ^^ 

54 

In  the  second  case  we  have  p  =  zry^  ,  and  with  this  value  the 

54       .       . 
formula  gives  -^  which  is  approximately  "981 8. 

219 
In  the  third  case  we  have  p  —  ^^^, ,  and  with  this  value  the 

^       1218 

OAQ 

formula    gives   -— ^  which  however  is  very  nearly  '9560  instead  of 

840 

•9540  as  Condorcet  states. 

742.  Condorcet's  next  example  seems  very  arbitrary  and  ob- 
scure.    His  words  are, 

Supposons  encore  que  robservation  ait  constate  que,  sur  vingt  mil- 
lions d'hommes,  un  seul  ait  vecu  120  ans,  et  que  la  plus  longue  vie 
ait  ete  de  130  ;  qu'un  homme  me  dise  que  quelqu'un  vient  de  mourir  a 
120  ans,  et  que  je  cherclie  la  probabilite  propre  de  cet  eveneraent  :  je 
regarderai  d'abord  comme  iin  fait  unique,  celui  de  vivre  plus  de  130 
ans,  fait  que  je  suppose  n'etre  pas  arrive;  j'aurai  done  131  faits  dif- 
ferens,  dont  celui  de  moui'ir  a  120  ans  est  un  seul.     La  probabilite  de 

celui-ci  sera    ^^^^^,  o-,  ;   la  probabihte  moyenne  des   130  autres  sera 
20000131  '         ^  '' 

20000130  ,        ,  ,    ,.,.^.  .       ,  ,  130 

20000131  X  130  ^  ^"^'  ^"^  probabdite  propre  cherchee  sera  ^00002^00  ' 

1 

ou  environ 


15384 


743.  Condorcet's  next  example  seems  also  arbitrary.  His 
words  are, 

Cette  methode  s'appliquera  egalement  aux  dvcnemens  indetermines. 
Ainsi,  en  continuant  le  meme  exemple,  si  le  temoin  a  dit  seulement 
que  Ton  a  deux  fois  amenc  la  meme  carte,  sans  la  nommer,  alors  ces  dix 

cvenemens,  ayant  cliacun  la  probabilite  y—  - ,    -—  exprimera  leur  pro- 


CONDORCET.  405 

.  .  2 

babilite  rooyenne;  — r-   exprimera  de  meine  celle  des  45  aiitras   evene- 

mens  ayaut  cliacun  la  probabilite  y—  :  ainsi  la  probabilite  propre  de 

I'evenemeiit  sera  - . 

o 

Condorcet  himself  observes  that  it  may  appear  singular  that 
the  result  in  this  case  is  less  than  that  which  was  obtained  in 
Ai't.  74;0 ;  so  that  a  man  is  less  trustworthy  when  he  merely  says 
that  he  has  seen  the  same  card  drawn  twice,  than  when  he  tells  us 
in  addition  what  card  it  was  that  he  saw  drawn  twice.  Condorcet 
tries  to  explain  this  apparent  singularity;  but  not  with  any  ob- 
vious success. 

The  singularity  however  seems  entirely  to  arise  from  Con- 
dorcet's  own  arbitrary  choice  ;  the  rule  which  he  himself  lays  do^\ai 
requires  him  to  estimate  la  prohabilite  moyenne  de  tons  les  autres 
evenemens,  and  he  estimates  this  mean  probability  differently  in 
the  two  cases,  and  apparently  without  sufficient  reason  for  the  dif- 
ference. 

744.  Condorcet's  next  example  is  as  follows  :  We  are  told  that 
a  person  with  two  dice  has  five  times  successively  thrown  higher 
than  10 ;  find  the  prohabilite  lyropre.  With  two  dice  the  number 
thrown  may  be  2,  3,  ...  up  to  12  ;  the  respective  probabilities  are 

86'    36'    36'    36'    36'    36'    36'    36'    36'    36'    36* 

_,        ,    ,            1         c          ,     .     11  X  12  X  13  X 14  X  15      ,,    ^   . 
The  whole  number  ol  events  is  r^ ,    that  is 

L? 

3003 ;  and  of  these  only  6  belong  to  the  proposed  combination. 

1 

Since  the  probability  of  these  6  throws  is  :r^  their  mean  proba- 
bility is  -^ -^ .     The  mean  probability  of  the  other  throws  will 

u  X  J-^ 

11^  .  2997 

he  ^gc)-  X  12^  *     ^^^^^  ^^^®  prohahiliie  propre  is  g  ><  ir  +  2997  * 

It  is  obvious  that  all  this  is  very  arbitrary.  Wlien  Condorcet 
says  there  are  6  throws  belonging  to  the  proposed  combination  he 
means  that  all  the  throws  may  be  12,  or  all  11,  or  four  12  and  one 
11,  or  three  12  and  two  11,  . . .  And  he  says  the  mean  probability  is 


40G  CONDORCET. 

But  if  we  consider  tlie  different  orders  in  which  these 


6x  12^* 

throws  can  occur  we  may  say  that  the  whole  number  is  2^  and  the 

1   /  1        2  \^  1 

mean  probabihty  ^  ( 35  +  35 j  ^  ^^^^^  ^^  2^2" ' 

Again  let  us  admit  that  there  are  8003  cases  in  all,  and  that  of 
these  only  6  belong  to  the  proposed  combination.  The  other 
2997  cases  form  two  species,  namely  those  in  which  every  throw  is 
below  11,  and  those  in  which  some  throws  are  below  11  and  the 

ir 

others  above  10 ;  when  Condorcet  takes  -—^ — -^  as  the  mean 
probability,  he  forgets  this  division  of  species  and  only  con- 
siders the  first  species.     He  should  take         ^  [  1  —  ^-^1   instead 

ir 


of 


2997  X  12'  • 


7-i5.  Suppose  two  classes  of  events  A  and  B;  let  the  pro- 
bability of  an  A  he  a  and  the  probability  of  a  i>  be  ^ ;  let  there 
be  m  events  A  and  n  events  B.  The  ]^'t^obabilite  projore  of  an 
assigned  event  of  the  class  B  will  be,  according  to  Condorcet's 
practice, 

h  ^1     .    •  (m  +  n—  1)  h 

-""--■■" ^       ,  that    IS      ; -: —,    . 

ma  4-  {ii  —  l)u      -.  ma  +  {^ni  +  Zr  —  'I)  0 

m  -\-  n—1 

21) 

If  m  and  n  be   equal   and  very  large    this    becomes  ^  .     If 

a  -p  ou 

we  suppose    h    extremely  small  and   consequently  a  very  nearly 

unity  we  obtain  2h  as  an  approximate  value. 

716.  Condorcet  proceeds  to  apply  his  doctrine  to  the  credi- 
bility of  two  statements  in  the  History  of  Home.     He  says, 

Je  vais  maintenant  essay er  de  faire  a  nne  question  de  critique 
rapplication  des  principes  que  je  viens  d'etablir.  Newton  paroit  etre 
le  premier  qui  ait  eu  I'idee  d'appliquer  le  calcul  des  probabilites  a  la 
critique  des  faits.  II  propose,  dans  son  ouvrage  sur  la  clironologie, 
d'employer  la  connoissance  de  la  durce  moyenne  des  generations  et  des 
regncs,  telle  que  I'experience  nous  la  donue,  soit  pour  fixer  d'une 
manicre  du  moins  approchee,  des  points  de  clironologie  fort  incertains, 


CONDORCET.  407 

soit  pour  juger  dii  plus  on  clii  moins  de  coiifiance  que  meritent  les 
differens  systemes  imagines  pour  concilier  entr'elles  des  ^poques  qui 
paroissent  se  contredire. 

Condorcet  names  Freret  as  having  opposed  this  apphcation  of 
the  Theory  of  Probabihty,  and  Yoltaire  as  having  supported  it ;  but 
he  gives  no  references. 

747.  According  to  some  historians  the  whole  duration  of  the 
reigns  of  the  seven  kings  of  Rome  was  257  years.  Condorcet  pro- 
poses to  examine  the  credibility  of  this  statement.  He  assumes 
that  in  an  elective  monarchy  we  may  suppose  that  a  king  at  the 
date  of  his  election  will  be  between  30  years  old  and  60  years  old. 
He  adopts  De  Moivre's  hypothesis  respecting  human  mortality  ; 
this  hypothesis,  as  Condorcet  uses  it,  amounts  to  assuming  that 
the  number  of  people  at  any  e230ch  who  are  y  years  old  is 
h  (90  —  ?/),  where  h  is  some  constant,  and  that  of  these  Iz  die  every 
year. 

Let  n  denote  the  greatest  number  of  years  which  the  youngest 
elected  king  can  live,  m  the  greatest  number  of  years  which  the 
oldest  elected  king  can  live  ;  then  the  probability  that  a  single 
reign  will  last  just  r  years  is  the  coefficient  of  ^  in  the  expan- 
sion of 

ill  - m  -\-X)x(X-x)- .t"^^  +  rr"^" 

A  few  words  will  be  necessary  to  shew  how  this  formula  can  be 
verified.  It  follows  from  our  hypothesis  that  the  number  of  per- 
sons from  whom  the  king  must  be  elected  is 

h  [n  +  (?i  -  1)  +  (?i  -  2)  +  . . .  +  m], 
that  is  Iz  — ^—  [n  —  m  4- 1).  And  if  r  be  less  than  m  +  1  the  num- 
ber of  persons  who  die  in  the  r*'^  year  will  be  I:  {n  —  m  +  1)  ;  if  r  be 
between  m  4- 1  and  n+1,  both  inclusive,  the  number  who  die  in 
the  r^^  year  will  be  k  {n  —  r  +  1)  ;  if  r  be  greater  than  n  +  1  the 
number  who  die  in  the  r"'  year  will  be  zero.  Now  the  coefficient 
of  ic*"  in  the  expansion  of 

1-x  (1  -  -^j' 


408  CONDORCET. 

will  be  found  to  be  n  —  m  +  1  if  r  is  less  than  m  +  l,  and  0  if  r  is 
greater  than  n  +  1,  and  in  other  cases  to  be  w  -  r  +  1. 

748,  Hence  the  probability  that  the  duration  of  seven  reigns 
will  amount  to  just  257  years  is  the  coefficient  of  ic^"  in  the  expan- 
sion of  the  seventh  power  of 

{n  -  m  +  1)  a^  (1  -  x)  -^^  x"""^ 
(1  —  x)  — ^ —  (n  -  m  +  1) 

Now  Condorcet  takes  n  =  60  and  m  =  SO;  and  he  says  that  the 
value  of  the  required  coefficient  is  '000792,  which  we  will  assume 
he  has  calculated  correctly. 

Thus  he  has  obtained  the  probability  in  the  ordinary  sense, 
which  he  denotes  by  P;  he  requires  the  j)rohahilite  projyre.  He 
considers  there  are  414  events  possible,  as  the  reigns  may  have 
any  duration  in  years  between  7  and  420.     Thus  the  mean  proba- 

.1  -P 

bility  of  all  the  other  events  is    ,        ;  and  so  the  prohahilite  p^opre 

413P  ,         1 

1  ^  412P  '  ^i^^^^^^^S- 


IS 


749.  Condorcet  says  that  other  historians  assign  140  years  in- 
stead of  257  years  for  the  duration  of  the  reigns  of  the  kings. 
He  says  the  ordinary  probability  of  this  is  '008887,  which  we 
may  denote  by  Q.     He  then  makes  the  prohahilite  propre  to  be 

which  IS  more  than  - . 


He  seems  here  to  take  413,  and  not  414,  as  the  whole  number 
of  events. 

750.  Condorcet  then  proceeds  to  compare  three  events,  namely 
that  of  257  years'  duration,  that  of  140  years'  duration,  and  what 
he  calls  wi  autre  dvenement  mdetermine  quelconque  qui  auroit  pu 
avoir  lieu.    He  makes  the  prohahilites  jyrojn-es  to  be  respectively 

411P  411^ 1-P-Q 

410 (P+  Q)  +  i'  410 (p+  Q)  + 1  ""'"'^  n^pToy+i' 

3      37     10 

which  are  approximately  — , ,    '-—  ,    -—  . 

•^  50      oO      50 


COXDORCET.  409 

Here  again  he  seems  to  take  413  as  the  whole  number  of 
events. 

He  proceeds  to  combine  these  probabihties  with  probabilities 
arising  from  testimony  borne  to  the  first  or  second  event, 

751.  Condorcet  considers  another  statement  which  he  finds  in 
Roman  History,  namely  that  the  augur  Accius  Nsevius  cut  a  stone 

with  a  razor.     Condorcet  takes     rv/^rir^rvrv  ^s  the  ordinaiy  proba- 
bility, and  then  by  Art.  745  makes  the  prohahilite  ijropre  to  be 

2 
1000000  * 

752.  We  have  spent  a  long  space  on  Condorcet's  memoir,  on 
account  of  the  reputation  of  the  author ;  but  we  fear  that  the 
reader  will  conclude  that  we  have  given  to  it  far  more  attention 
than  it  deserves.  It  seems  to  us  to  be  on  the  whole  excessively 
arbitrary,  altogether  unpractical,  and  in  parts  very  obscure, 

753.  We  have  in  various  plaices  expressed  so  decidedly  our 
opinion  as  to  the  obscurity  and  inutility  of  Condorcet's  investiga- 
tions that  it  will  be  just  to  notice  the  opinions  which  other  writers 
have  formed. 

Gouraud  devotes  pages  89 — 101?  of  his  work  to  Condorcet,  and 
the  following  defects  are  noticed :  Un  style  embarrasse,  denue  de 
justesse  et  de  coloris,  une  philosophie  souvent  obscure  ou  bizarre, 
une  anatyse  que  les  meilleurs  juges  ont  trouvee  confuse.  With  this 
drawback  Condorcet  is  praised  in  terms  of  such  extravagant  eulogy, 
that  we  are  tempted  to  apply  to  Gouraud  the  reflexion  which  Du- 
gald  Stewart  makes  in  reference  to  Voltaire,  who  he  says  "  is  so 
lavish  and  undistinguishing  in  his  praise  of  Locke,  as  almost  to 
justify  a  doubt  whether  he  had  ever  read  the  book  Avhich  he  extols 
so  highly."     Stewart's  Works,  edited  hy  Hamilton,  Vol.  i.  j)age  220. 

Galloway  speaks  of  Condorcet's  Essay  as  ''  a  work  of  gi'eat  in- 
genuity, and  abounding  with  interesting  remarks  on  subjects  of 
the  highest  importance  to  humanity."  Ai'ticle  Prohahilitij  in  the 
Encyclopcedia  Britan  nica. 

Laplace  in  his  brief  sketch  of  the  history  of  the  subject  does 
not  name  Condorcet ;  he  refers  however  to  the  kind  of  questions 


410  CONDOECET. 

which  Condorcet  considers  and  says,  Tant  de  passions,  d'interets 
divers  et  de  circonstances  compliquent  les  questions  relatives  a 
ces  objets,  qu'elles  sont  presque  toujours  insolubles.  Theorie...des 
Froh.  page  cxxxviii. 

Poisson  names  Condorcet  expressly;  with  respect  to  his  Prelimi- 
nary Discourse,  he  says,  ...  ou  sont  developpees  avec  soin  les  con- 
siderations propres  a  montrer  I'utilite  de  ce  genre  de  recherches. 
And  after  referring  to  some  of  Laplace's  investigations  Poisson 
adds,  ...  il  est  juste  de  dire  que  c'est  a  Condorcet  quest  due  I'idee 
ingenieuse  de  faire  dependre  la  solution,  du  princijDe  de  Bayes,  en 
considerant  successivement  la  culpabilite  et  I'innocence  de  I'accuse, 
comme  une  cause  inconnue  du  jugement  prononce,  qui  est  alors  le 
fait  observe,  duquel  il  s'agit  de  deduire  la  probabilite  de  cette 
cause.     Recherches  sur  la  Proh. . . .  page  2. 

We  have  already  referred  to  John  Stuart  Mill,  see  Art.  QGo. 
One  sentence  of  his  may  perhaps  not  have  been  specially  aimed 
at  Condorcet,  but  it  may  well  be  so  applied.  Mr  Mill  says,  "  It  is 
obvious,  too,  that  even  when  the  probabilities  are  derived  from  ob- 
servation and  experiment,  a  very  slight  improvement  in  the  data, 
by  better  observations,  or  by  taking  into  fuller  consideration  the 
special  circumstances  of  the  case,  is  of  more  use  than  the  most 
elaborate  application  of  the  calculus  to  probabilities  founded  on  the 
data  in  their  jDrevious  state  of  inferiority."  Logic,  Vol.  ii.  page  65. 
Condorcet  seems  really  to  have  fancied  that  valuable  results  could 
be  obtained  from  any  data,  however  imperfect,  by  using  formulae 
with  an  adequate  supply  of  signs  of  integration. 


CHAPTER   XVIII. 


TREMBLEY. 

75^.  We  have  now  to  examine  a  series  of  memoirs  by 
Trembley.     He  was  born  at  Geneva  in  1749,  and  died  in  1811. 

The  first  memoir  is  entitled  Disquisitio  Elementaris  circa  Cal- 
culinn  Prohahilium. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  Commentationes  Societatis 
Regice  Scientiarum  Gottingensis,  Yol.  Xll.  The  volume  is  for  the 
years  1793  and  1791^ ;  and  the  date  of  publication  is  1796.  The 
memoir  occupies  pages  99 — 136  of  the  mathematical  portion  of 
the  volume. 

755.  The  memoir  begitis  thus  : 

Plurimae  extant  hie  et  ilUc  sparsae  meditationes  analyticae  circa  cal- 
culum  Probabilium,  quas  hie  recensere  non  est  animus.  Quae  cum 
plerumque  quaestiones  j)ai^iculares  spectarent,  summi  Geometrae  la 
Place  et  la  Grange  hanc  theoriam  generalius  tractare  sunt  aggressi, 
auxilia  derivantes  ex  intimis  calculi  integralium  visceribus,  et  eximios 
quidem  fructus  inde  perceperunt.  Cum  autem  tota  Probabilium  theoria 
principiis  simplicibus  et  obviis  sit  innixa,  quae  nihil  aliud  fere  requirunt 
quam  doctrinam  combinationum,  et  pleraeque  difficultates  in  enume- 
randis  et  distinguendis  casibus  versentur,  e  re  visum  est  easdem  quaes- 
tiones generaliores  methodo  elementari  tractare,  sine  uUo  alieno  auxilio. 
Cujus  tentaminis  primum  sj^ecimen  hae  paginae  complectuntur,  continent 
quippe  solutiones  elementares  Problematum  generaliorum  quae  vir 
illustrissimus  la  Grange  soluta  dedit  in  Commentariis  Academiae  Regiae 
Berolinensis  pro  anno  1775.  Si  haec  Geometris  non  displicuerint,  alias 
deinde  ejusdem  generis  cUlucidationes,  deo  juvante  ipsis  proponam. 

756.  The  intention  expressed  at  the  end  of  this  paragTaph  was 


412  TREMBLE  Y. 

carried  into  effect  in  a  memoir  in  the  next  volume  of  the  Gottin- 
gen  Commentationes.  The  present  memoir  discusses  nine  problems, 
most  of  which  are  to  be  found  in  De  Moivre's  Doctrine  of  Chances. 
To  this  work  Trembley  accordingly  often  refers,  and  his  references 
obviously  shew  that  he  used  the  second  edition  of  De  Moivre's 
work ;  we  shall  change  these  references  into  the  corresponding 
references  to  the  third  edition. 

In  this  and  other  memoirs  Trembley  proposes  to  give  elemen- 
tary investigations  of  theorems  which  had  been  previously  treated 
by  more  difficult  methods  ;  but  as  we  shall  see  he  frequently  leaves 
his  results  really  undemonstrated. 

7o7.  The  first  problem  is,  to  find  the  chance  that  an  event 
shall  happen  exactly  h  times  in  a  trials,  the  chance  of  its  haj)peniug 
in  a  single  trial  being  p.     Trembley  obtains  the  well  known  result, 

a 

p^  (1  —  i^Y    '  ^®  ^^^^^  ^li®  modern  method ;  see  Art.  257. 


a 


-h 


758.  The  second  problem  is  to  find  the  chance  that  the  event 
shall  happen  at  least  h  times.  Trembley  gives  and  demonstrates 
independently  both  the  formulae  to  which  we  have  already  drawn 
attention  ;  see  Art.  172.  He  says,  longum  et  taediosum  foret  has 
formulas  inter  se  comparare  a  priori;  but  as  we  have  seen  in 
Art.  174  the  comparison  of  the  formulae  is  not  really  difficult. 

759.  The  third  problem  consists  of  an  application  of  the  second 
problem  to  the  Problem  of  Poiyits,  in  the  case  of  tw^o  players  ;  the 
fourth  problem  is  that  of  Points  in  the  case  of  three  players ;  and 
the  fifth  problem  is  that  of  Points  in  the  case  of  four  players.  The 
results  coincide  with  those  of  De  Moivre;  see  Art.  267. 

760.  Trembley's  next  three  problems  are  on  the  Duration  of 
Play.  He  begins  with  De  Moivre's  Problem  LXV,  which  in  effect 
supposes  one  of  the  players  to  have  an  unlimited  capital ;  see 
Arts.  807,  309.  Trembley  gives  De  Moivre's  second  mode  of 
solution,  but  his  investigation  is  unsatisfactory ;  for  after  havino- 
found  in  succession  the  first  six  terms  of  the  series  in  brackets,  he 
says  Perspicua  nunc  est  lex  progressionis,  and  accordingly  writes 
down  the  general  term  of  the  series.  Trembley  thus  leaves  the 
main  difficulty  quite  untouched. 


TREMBLEY.  413 

7(31.  Trembley's  seventh  problem  is  De  Moivre's  Problem  LXiv, 
and  he  gives  a  result  equivalent  to  that  on  De  Moivre's  page  207; 
see  Art.  806.  But  here  again  after  investigating  a  few  terms  the 
main  difficulty  is  left  untouched  mth  the  words  Perspicua  nunc 
est  lex  progressionis.  Trembley  says,  Eodem  redit  solutio  Cel. 
la  Grange,  licet  eaedem  formulae  non  prodeant.  This  seems  to 
imply  that  Lagrange's  formulae  take  a  dilterent  shape.  Trembley 
.probably  refers  to  Lagrange's  second  solution  which  is  the  most 
completely  worked  out ;  see  Art.  583, 

Trembley  adds  in  a  Scholium  that  by  the  aid  of  this  problem 
we  can  solve  that  which  is  LXVII.  in  De  Moivre  ;  finishing  with 
these  words,  in  secunda  enim  formula  fieri  debet  c  =]p  —  1,  which 
appear  to  be  quite  erroneous. 

762.  Trembley's  eighth  problem  is  the  second  in  Lagrange's 
memoir ;  see  Art.  580  :  the  chance  of  one  event  is  p  and  of  an- 
other q,  find  the  chance  that  in  a  given  number  of  trials  the  first 
shall  happen  at  least  h  times  and  the  second  at  least  c  times. 
Trembley  puts  Lagrange's  solution  in  a  more  elementary  form,  so 
as  to  avoid  the  Theory  of  Finite  Differences. 

763.  Trembley's  ninth  problem  is  the  last  in  Lagrange's  me- 
moir ;  see  Art.  587.     Trembley  gives  a  good  solution. 

76-t.  The  next  memoir  is  entitled  De  Prohahilttate  Causarum 
ah  effectihus  oriunda. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  Comm.  Soc.  Reg....GoU. 
Yol.  XIII.  The  volume  is  for  the  years  1795 — 1798 ;  the  date  of 
publication  is  1799.  The  memoir  occupies  pages  64 — 119  of  the 
mathematical  portion  of  the  volume. 

765.     The  memoir  begins  thus  : 

Hanc  materiam  pertractarunt  eximii  Geometrae,  ac  potissimum  Cel. 
la  Place  in  Commentariis  Academiae  Parisinensis.  Cum  autem  in 
hiijusce  generis  Problematibus  solvendis  sublimior  et  ardua  analysis 
fuerit  adliibita,  easdem  qiiaestiones  metliodo  elementari  ac  idoneo  usii 
doctrinae  serierum  aggredi  operae  pretium  diixi.  Qua  ratione  haec  altera 
pars  calculi  Probabihum  ad  theoriam  combinationum  reduceretur,  sicut 
et  primam  reduxi  in  dissertatione  ad  Kegiam  Societateui  transmissa. 


41i  TREMBLE  Y. 

Primarias  quaestiones  hie  breviter  attingere    couabor,   methodo   diluci- 
dandae  imprimis  intentiis. 

^QQ.  The  first  problem  is  the  following.  A  bag  contains  an 
infinite  number  of  white  balls  and  black  balls  in  an  unknown 
ratio ;  p  white  balls  and  q  black  have  been  drawn  out  in  ^  +  ^ 
drawings  ;  what  is  the  chance  that  m  +  n  new  drawings  will  give 
m  white  and  w  black  balls  ? 

The  known  result  is 

\m  -f-  n  ^  ' 


m    It 


that  is, 


1  x^  {1  -xydx 

■^  0 

I  m  +  n     \)yi-\-  p   \n-{-q   \p  -\-  q-\-l 


\'m\n       \p    \q\'m-\-p-\-7i+q-\-l 


Trembley  refers  to  the  memoir  which  w^e  have  cited  in 
Art.  551,  where  this  result  had  been  given  by  Laplace  ;  see  also 
Art.  704. 

Trembley  obtains  the  result  by  ordinary  Algebra  ;  the  investi- 
gations are  only  approximate,  the  error  being  however  inappreci- 
able when  the  number  of  balls  is  infinite. 

If  each  ball  is  replaced  after  being  drawn  we  can  obtain  an 
exact  solution  of  the  problem  by  ordinary  Algebra,  as  we  shall  see 
when  we  examine  a  memoir  by  Prevost  and  Lhuilier ;  and  of  course 
if  the  number  of  the  balls  is  supposed  infinite  it  will  be  indifferent 
whether  we  replace  each  ball  or  not,  so  that  we  obtain  indirectly 
an  exact  elementary  demonstration  of  the  important  result  which 
Trembley  establishes  approximately. 

767-  We  proceed  to  another  problem  discussed  by  Trem- 
bley. A  bag  is  known  to  contain  a  very  large  number  of  balls 
which  are  white  or  black,  the  ratio  being  unknown.  In  p-\-q 
drawings  p  white  balls  and  q  black  have  been  drawn.  Required 
the  probability  that  the  ratio  of  the  white  to  the  black  lies  between 
zero  and  an  assigned  fraction.  This  question  Trembley  proceeds 
to  consider  at  great  length  ;  he  supposes  p)  and  q  very  large  and 
obtains  approximate  results. 

If  the   assigned  fraction   above   referred  to   be   denoted   by 


TREMELEY.  415 

— ^^- 6,  lie  obtains  as  the  numerator  of  the  required  probability, 

approximately 

\p  +  <t      )    \p  +  q      )     L     pq  +  {p  +  qf  S' 

\  p   \q 
The  denominator  would  be     ' ,,  . 

Trembley  refers  to  two  places  in  which  Laplace  had  given  this 
result;  they  are  the  Hist  de  T  Acad....  Par  is  for  1778,  page  270, 
and  for  1783  page  445.  In  the  Theorie...des  Frob.  Laplace  does 
not  reproduce  the  general  formula ;  he  confines  himself  to  suppos- 

.7)  X 

ing  —^ —  —0  =  --  see  pao^e  379  of  the  work. 

Trembley's  methods  are  laborious,  and  like  many  other  at- 
tempts to  bring  high  mathematical  investigations  into  more 
elementary  forms,  would  probably  cost  a  student  more  trouble 
than  if  he  were  to  set  to  work  to  enlarge  his  mathematical  know- 
ledge and  then  study  the  original  methods. 

7G8.  Trembley  follows  Laplace  in  a  numerical  application 
relating  to  the  births  of  boys  and  girls  at  Vitteaux  in  Bourgogne. 
Laplace  first  gave  this  in  the  Hist,  de  V  A  cad....  Paris  for  1783, 
page  448;  it  is  in  the  Theorie . . .  des  Proh.  page  380.  It  appears 
that  at  Vitteaux  in  five  years  212  girls  were  born  to  203  boys. 
It  is  curious  that  Laplace  gives  no  information  in  the  latter  work 
of  a  more  recent  date  than  he  gave  in  the  Hist,  de  V Acad.... Paris 
for  1783  ;  it  would  have  been  interesting  to  know  if  the  anomaly 
still  continued  in  the  births  at  Vitteaux. 

769.  We  may  observe  that  Laplace  treats  the  problem  of 
births  as  analogous  to  that  of  drawing  black  and  white  balls  from  a 
bag.  So  he  arrives  at  this  result ;  if  we  draw  212  black  balls  to  203 
white  balls  out  of  a  bag,  the  chance  is  about  '67  that  the  black 
balls  in  the  bag  are  more  numerous  than  the  white.  It  is  not 
very  easy  to  express  this  result  in  words  relating  to  births  ;  Laplace 
says  in  the  Hist,  de  V  Acad....  Par  is,  la  difference  "670198  sera  la 


•ilO  TREMBLE  Y. 

probability  qua  Viteaux,  la  2:)ossibilite  des  naissances  des  filles  est 
superieure  h  celle  des  naissances  des  gardens;  in  the  Theorie... 
des  F7vh.  he  says,  la  superiorite  de  la  facilite  des  naissances  des 
filles,  est  done  indiquee  par  ces  observations,  avec  une  probabilite 
egale  k  '67.  These  phrases  seem  much  better  adapted  to  the  idea 
to  be  expressed  than  Trembley's,  Probabilitas  numerum  puellarum 
superaturum  esse  numerum  puerorum  erit  =  •67141. 

770.  Trembley  now  takes  the  following  problem.  From  a 
basf  containing;  white  balls  and  black  balls  in  a  larg^e  number  but 
in  an  unknown  ratio  j^  white  balls  and  q  black  have  been  drawn ; 
required  the  chance  that  if  2a  more  drawings  are  made  the  white 
balls  shall  not  exceed  the  black.  This  problem  leads  to  a  series 
of  which  the  sum  cannot  be  found  exactly.  Trembley  gives  some 
investigations  respecting  the  series  which  seem  of  no  use,  and  of 
which  he  himself  makes  no  application ;  these  are  on  his  pages 
103 — 105.  On  his  page  106  he  gives  a  rough  approximate  value 
of  the  sum.  He  says,  Similem  seriem  refert  Gel.  la  Place.  This 
refers  to  the  Hist  de  V Acad.... Paris  for  1778,  page  280.  But  the 
word  similem  must  not  be  taken  too  strictly,  for  Laplace's  approxi- 
mate result  is  not  the  same  as  Trembley's. 

Laplace  applies  his  result  to  estimate  the  probability  that  more 
boys  than  girls  will  be  born  in  a  given  year.  This  is  not  repeated 
in  the  Theorie... des  Proh.,  but  is  in  fact  included  in  what  is  there 
given,  pages  397 — 401,  which  first  appeared  in  the  Hist,  de 
r Acad.... Paris  for  1783,  page  458. 

771.  Trembley  now  takes  another  of  Laplace's  problems, 
namely  that  discussed  by  Laplace  in  the  Memoires . . .  par  divers 
So.vans,  Vol.  vi.  page  633. 

Two  players,  whose  respective  skills  are  unknown,  play  on  the 
condition  that  he  who  first  gains  7i  games  over  his  adversary  shall 
take  the  whole  stake ;  at  a  certain  stage  when  A  wants  f  games 
and  B  wants  h  games  they  agree  to  leave  off  playing :  required 
to  know  how  the  stake  should  be  divided.  Suppose  it  were  given 
that  the  skill  of  ^  is  a?  and  that  of  jB  is  1  —  x.  Then  we  know 
by  Art.  172  that  B  ought  to  have  the  fraction  <j)  (x)  of  the  stake, 
where 


TREMBLEY.  417 


.  /  N       /I        \m  (-,  ^      ^  m(m  —  1)         x^ 


m  (m  —  1)  (m  —  2)         x^ 

+     ^ 


where  m  =f+  7i  —  1. 

Now  if  X  represents  ^'s  skill  the  probability  that  in  2n  —f—  h 
games  A  would  win  7i  —f  and  B  would  win  n  —  li  is  ic""-^  (1  —  x)""'^, 
disregarding  a  numerical  coefficient  which  we  do  not  want. 

Hence  if  A  wins  n  —f  games  and  B  wins  n  —  h,  which  is  now 
the  observed  event,  we  infer  that  the  chance  that  A's  skill  is  x  is 

x""-^  (1  -  x)''-""  dx 


f 

J  a 


x^-f  (1  _  xf-''  dx 

Therefore  the  fraction  of  the  stake  to  which  B  is  entitled  is 

<f>  {x)  x''-'  (1  -  a?)"-'  dx 


L 


x""-^  (1  -  xy-""  dx 


All  this  involves  only  Laplace's  ordinary  theory.  Now  the 
following  is  Trembley's  method.  Consider  ^  (x) ;  the  first  term 
is  (1  —  xy ;  this  represents  the  chance  that  B  will  win  m  games 
running  on  the  supposition  that  his  skill  is  1  —  x.  If  we  do  not 
know  his  skill  a  ^7^iori  we  must  substitute  instead  of  (1  —  a?)"*  the 
chance  that  B  will  win  m  games  running,  computed  from  the 
observed  fact  that  he  has  won  7i  —  h  games  to  ^'s  n  —f  games. 
This  chance  is,  by  Art,  7Q6, 

Ui+f-l\2fi-f-h  +  l 

' ''"^^—j^r^r-  =  ^^  say. 

I  —  h  [2n  '^ 


Again  consider  the  term  rax  (1  -  xf'"^  in  0  ix).  This  represents 
the  chance  that  B  will  win  m  -  1  games  out  of  m,  on  the  suppo- 
sition that  his  skill  is  \-x.  If  we  do  not  know  his  skill  a  jpriori 
w^e  must  substitute  instead  of  this  the  chance  that  B  will  win 

27 


418  TREMBLEY 

m  —  1  games  out  of  m,  deduced  from  the  observed  fact  that  he  has 
won  n  —  h  games  to  ^'s  n  —/games.     This  chance  is,  by  Art.  760, 

m  (n  -/+  1)  j^ 

It  is  needless  to  go  farther,  as  the  principle  is  clear.     The  final 
result  is  that  the  fraction  of  the  stake  to  which  B  is  entitled  is 

[    ^-^  ^w+/-l  1.2  n-\-f-ln+f-2 

(/+  7,  -  1)  ...  (A  +  1)  {n  -/+  1)  {n  -/+  2)...(n-l) 


/-I  (^+/_l)(,^+/_2)...(n  +  l) 


This  process  is  the  most  interesting  in  Trembley's  memoir. 
Laplace  does  not  reproduce  this  problem  in  the  Theorie  . . .  des 
Prob. 

772.  Trembley  gives  some  remarks  to  shew  the  connexion 
between  his  own  methods  and  Laplace's.  These  amount  in  fact 
to  illustrations  of  the  use  of  the  Integral  Calculus  in  the  summa- 
tion of  series. 

For  example  he  gives  the  result  which  we  may  write  thus : 

j)  +  l      lp  +  2'^     1.2     p  +  3  1.2.3         p  +  4<'^"' 

p  +  q  +  1 

==!  X^{1-  txydx  =  -^  f'x^  (1  -  X^dx. 
Jo  *"        J  0 

773.  Trembley  remarks  that  problems  in  Probability  consist 
of  two  parts ;  first  the  formulae  must  be  exhibited  and  then  modes 
of  approximate  calculation  found.  He  proposes  to  give  one  ex- 
ample from  Laplace. 

Observation  indicates  that  the  ratio  of  the  number  of  boys 
born  to  the  number  of  girls  born  is  greater  at  London  than  at 
Paris. 

Laplace  says  :  Cette  difference  semble  indiquer  a  Londres  une 
plus  grande  facilite  pour  la  naissance  des  gardens,  il  s'agit  de  deter- 
miner combien  cela  est  probable.     See  Hist  de  V Acad. .,,  Paris 


TREMBLEY.  419 

for  1778,  page  304,  for  17S3,  page  419;  and  Theorie . . .  des  Proh. 
page  381. 

Trembley  says, 

Supponit  Cel.  la  Place  nates  esse  Parisiis  intra  certnm  tempus,  ^) 
puA-os  q  puellas,  Londini  autem  intra  aliud  temporis  spatiiim  p'  pueros 
q  puellas,  et  quaerit  Probabilitatem,  causam  quae  Parisiis  producit 
pueros  esse  efficaciorem  quam  Londini.  E  supra  dictis  sequitur  hanc 
Probabilitatem  rejDraesentari  per  formulam 


X' 


{l-xyx'P'([-xy'dxdx' 


y  (1  -  xf  x''  (1  -  x'Y  dxdx' 


Trembley  tben  gives  the  limits  of  the  integrations ;  in  the 
numerator  for  x  from  a^'  =  0  to  ic'  =  x,  and  then  for  x  from  a?  =  0 
to  x  =  l\  in  the  denominator  both  integrations  are  between  0 
and  1. 

Trembley  considers  the  numerator.  He  expands  x'^  (1  —  x'Y  in 
powers  of  x  and  integrates  from  a?'  =  0  to  x  =  x.  Then  he  expands 
x^  {1  —  xY  and  integrates  from  a;  =  0  to  a?  =  1  ;  he  obtains  a  result 
which  he  transforms  into  another  more  convenient  shape,  which 
he  might  have  obtained  at  once  and  saved  a  page  if  he  had  not 
expanded  x^  (1  —  xY-  Then  he  uses  an  algebraical  theorem  in 
order  to  effect  another  transformation ;  this  theorem  he  does  not 
demonstrate  generally,  but  infers  it  from  examining  the  first  three 
cases  of  it ;  see  his  page  113. 

We  will  demonstrate  his  final  result,  by  another  method.  We 
have 

jx    [L     x)ax-x      ^^'^i      lp'  +  2^      1.2     p'  +  S         J 

Multiply  by  x^  (1  -  xY  and  integrate  from  x  =  0  to  a;  =  1 ; 
thus  we  obtain  by  the  aid  of  known  formula 

[q  \p+p  +1  (  1     ^'1     p  +y + ^ 
p+p'+q  +  ^  I^TTi  ~  r  y  +  2  ]r+/T7T3 


q'  jq'  -  1)        1        (P  +  P+^)(P  +  P+^) 

"^      1.2       y  +  3   (p+2^'  +  2  +  3)(P+/  +  2  +  "^) 


27—2 


420  TREiMBLEY. 

This  result  as  we  have  said  Trembley  obtains,  though  he  goes 
through  more  steps  to  reach  it. 

Suppose  however  that  before  effecting  the  integration  with 
respect  to  x  we  use  the  following  theorem 

1  4       X       ,   ^'(^'-1)       orJ^  q'{q'-V){q'-^)       x^      , 


/  +  1      1/  +  2'^1.2     y  +  3  1.2.3  _p'  +  4 

=  (^  ~  ''^'  liTTT+T  ^  (/  +  2+1)  (/  +  2')  i^^ 


(P'  +  2'  + 1)  (/  +  2 )  (/  +  2'  - 1)  (1  -  •'^) 

^_ 2'(2'-l)(2'-2) ^  ,       ' 

(/  +  2+1)  {P  +  2')  (/  +  2'  - 1)  (P  +2-2)  (l-.^)^         . 

Then  by  integrating  with  respect  to  x,  we  obtain 
\qj\-q  |j9+p'  +  l     f         1  9^'  ^+y  +  g  +  g +^ 


y)4j/+£+</+2    Ip'+^'+l        (/^'■+^'+l)(/+^')  ^  +  2 


q{q~l) (7^+7y+g+g'+2)(^+/+g+g+l) 

It  is  in  fact  the  identity  of  these  two  results  of  the  final  inte- 
gration which  Trembley  assumes  from  observing  its  truth  when 
q  =  1,  or  2,  or  3. 

With  regard  to  the  theorem  we  have  given  above  we  may 
remark  that  it  may  be  obtained  by  examining  the  coefficient  of  a?*" 
on  the  two  sides  ;  the  identity  of  these  coefficients  may  be  estab- 
lished as  an  example  of  the  theory  of  partial  fractions. 

774.  Trembley  then  proceeds  to  an  approximate  summation 
of  the  series ;  his  method  is  most  laborious,  and  it  would  not  repay 
the  trouble  of  verification.  He  says  at  the  end,  Series  haec,  quae 
similis  est  seriei  quam  refert  Cel.  la  Place  ...  He  gives  no  refer- 
ence, but  he  i^robably  has  in  view  the  Hist,  de  VAcad Paris 

for  1778,  page  310. 

775.  We  have  next  to  consider  a  memoir  entitled  Recherches 
SUV  une  question  relative  au  calcid  des  prohahilites.  This  memoir  is 
published  in  the  volume  for  1794  and  l79o  of  the  Memoir es  de 


TREMBLEY.  421 

r Acad.... Berlin;  the  date  of  publication  is  1799:  tlie  memoir 
occupies  pages  69 — 108  of  tlie  mathematical  portion  of  the  volume. 
The  problem  discussed  is  that  which  we  have  noticed  in  Art.  44:8. 

776.  Trembley  refers  in  the  course  of  his  memoir  to  what  had 
been  done  by  De  Moivre,  Laplace  and  Euler.     He  says, 

L'analyse  dont  M.  Euler  fait  usage  dans  ce.  Memoire  est  tres-inge- 
nieuse  et  digne  de  ce  grand  geometre,  mais  comme  elle  est  un  peu 
iudirecte  et  qu'il  ne  seroit  pas  aise  de  I'appliquer  au  probleme  general 
dont  celui-ci  n'est  qu'un  cas  particulier,  j'ai  entrepris  de  traiter  la  chose 
directement  d'apres  la  doctrine  des  combinaisons,  et  de  donner  a  la 
question  toute  I'etendue  dont  elle  est  susceptible. 

777.  The  problem  in  the  degree  of  generality  which  Trembley 
gives  to  it  had  already  engaged  the  attention  of  De  Moivre ;  see 
ilrt.  293.  De  Moivre  begins  with  the  simpler  case  in  his  Pro- 
blem XXXIX,  and  then  briefly  indicates  how  the  more  general 
question  in  his  Problem  XLI.  is  to  be  treated.  Trembley  takes  the 
contrary  order,  beginning  Vvdth  the  general  question  and  then 
deducing  the  simpler  case. 

When  he  has  obtained  the  results  of  his  problem  Trembley 
modifies  them  so  as  to  obtain  the  results  of  the  problem  discussed 
by  Laplace  and  Euler.  This  he  does  very  briefly  in  the  manner 
we  have  indicated  in  Aii.  453. 

778.  Trembley  gives  a  numerical  example.  Suppose  that  a 
lottery  consists  of  90  tickets,  and  that  5  are  drawn  at  each  time ; 
then  he  obtains  74102  as  the  approximate  value  of  the  probability 
that  all  the  numbers  mil  have  been  drawn  in  100  drawings. 
Euler  had  obtained  the  result  -7419  in  the  work  which  we  have 
cited  in  Art.  456. 

779.  Trembley's  memoir  adds  little  to  what  had  been  given 
before.  In  fact  the  only  novelty  which  it  contains  is  the  investi- 
gation of  the  probability  that  n-1  kinds  of  faces  at  least  should 
come  up,  or  that  n-2  kinds  of  faces  at  least,  or  n  -  3,  and  so  on. 
The  result  is  analogous  to  that  which  had  been  given  by  Euler  and 
which  we  have  quoted  in  Ai^t.  458.  Nor  do  Trembley's  methods 
present  any  thing  of  importance  ;  they  are  in  fact  such  as  would 
naturally  occur  to  a  reader  of  De  Moivre's  book  if  he  wished  to 


422  TREMBLEY. 

reverse  the  order  which  De  Moivre  has  taken.  Trembley  does  not 
supply  general  demonstrations ;  he  begins  with  a  simple  case,  then 
he  proceeds  to  another  which  is  a  little  more  complex,  and  when 
the  law  which  governs  the  general  result  seems  obvious  he  enun- 
ciates it,  leaving  to  his  readers  to  convince  themselves  that  the  law 
is  universally  true. 

780.  Trembley  notices  the  subject  of  the  summation  of  a  cer- 
tain series  which  we  have  considered  in  Art.  460.  Trembley  says, 
M.  Euler  remarque  que  dans  ce  cas  la  somme  de  la  suite  qui  donne 
la  probabilite,  pent  s'exprimer  par  des  produits.  Cela  pent  se  de- 
montrer  par  le  calcul  integral,  par  la  methode  suivante  qui  est 
fort  simple.  But  in  what  follows  in  the  memoir,  there  is  no  use  of 
the  Integral  Calculus,  and  the  demonstration  seems  quite  unsatis- 
factory. The  result  is  verified  when  a?  =  1,  2,  3,  or  4  and  then  is 
assumed  to  be  universally  true.  And  these  verifications  them- 
selves are  unsatisfactory;  for  in  each  case  r  is  put  successively 
equal  to  1,  2,  8,  4,  and  the  law  which  appears  to  hold  is  assumed 
to  hold  universally. 

Trembley  also  proposes  to  demonstrate  that  the  sum  of  the 
series  is  zero,  if  ti  be  greater  than  rx.  The  demonstration  how- 
ever is  of  the  same  unsatisfactory  character,  and  there  is  this  ad- 
ditional defect.  Trembley  supposes  successively  that  n  =  r  (a?  +  1), 
7i  =  r{x  +  2),  n  =  7^  {x+S),  and  so  on.  But  besides  these  cases  ?i 
may  have  any  value  between  rx  and  r  (x  +  l),  or  between  r  {x+1) 
and  r  {x+2),  and  so  on.  Thus,  in  fact,  Trembley  makes  a  most 
imperfect  examination  of  the  possible  cases. 

781.  Trembley  deduces  from  his  result  a  formula  suitable  for 
approximate  numerical  calculation,  for  the  case  in  which  n  and  x 
are  large,  and  r  small ;  his  formula  agrees  with  one  given  by  La- 
place in  the  Hist  de  V Acad.,.. Paris  1783,  as  he  himself  observes. 
Trembley  obtains  his  formula  by  repeated  use  of  an  approximation 
which  he  establishes  by  ordinary  Algebraical  expansion,  namely 

('-3'=-(-S)- 

Trembley  follows  Laplace  in  the  numerical  example  which 
we  have  noticed  in  Art.  455.     Trembley  moreover  finds  that  in 


TREMBLE  Y.  423 

about  86927  drawings  there  is  an  even  chance  that  all  the  tickets 
except  one  will  have  been  drawn ;  and  he  j^i'oceeds  nearly  to  the 
end  of  the  calculation  for  the  case  in  which  all  the  tickets  except 
two  are  required  to  be  drawn. 

782.  The  next  memoir  is  entitled  Becherches  sur  la  mortalite 
cle  la  petite  verole. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  Memoir es  de  VAcad....Be7'lin 
for  1796  ;  the  date  of  publication  is  1799  :  the  memoir  occupies 
pages  17 — 38  of  the  mathematical  portion  of  the  volume. 

783.  This  memoir  is  closely  connected  with  one  by  Daniel 
Bernoulli ;  see  Art.  398.  Its  object  may  be  described  as  twofold; 
first,  it  solves  the  problem  on  the  hypotheses  of  Daniel  Bernoulli 
by  common  Algebra  without  the  Integral  Calculus ;  secondly,  it 
examines  how  far  those  hypotheses  are  verified  by  facts.  The 
memoir  is  interesting  and  must  have  been  valuable  in  a  practical 
point  of  view  at  the  date  of  publication. 

784.  Let  m  and  n  have  the  same  signification  as  in  Daniel 
Bernoulli's  memoir ;  see  Art.  402  :  that  is,  suppose  that  every  year 
small-pox  attacks  1  in  n  of  those  who  have  not  had  the  disease, 
and  that  1  in  m  of  those  who  are  attacked  dies. 

Let  a^  denote  a  given  number  of  births,  and  suppose  that 
a^,  a^,  a^,  ...  denote  the  number  of  those  who  are  alive  at  the  end 
of  1,  2,  3,  ...  years :  then  Trembley  shews  that  the  number  of  per- 
sons alive  at  the  beginning  of  the  x^^  year  who  have  not  had  the 
small-pox  is 


i-i+i(i-ir 

m      711  V        'nJ 


For  let  h^  denote  the  number  alive  at  the  beginning  of  the  a^"' 
year  who  have  not  had  the  small-pox,  and  ^^^^  the  number  at  the 
beginning  of  the  {x  +  1)*^  year.     Then  in  the  x^^'  year  small-pox 

attacks  —  persons  ;  thus  h^  (l j  would  be  alive  at  the  begin- 
ning of  the  next  year  without  having  had  the  small-pox  if  none  of 
them  died  by  other  diseases.    We  must  therefore  find  how  many  of 


42tt  TREMBLEY. 


these  h^fl 1  die  of  other  diseases,  and  subtract.    Now  the  total 

number  who  die  of  other  diseases  during  the  x^^  year  is 

_  A 

h 
these  die  out  of  the  number  a^ ~ ,     HencO;  by  proportion,  the 

number  who  die  out  of  &^  f  1  —  -  ]  is 


a^  —  a, 


mn 


K    \'     ""~W- 


Therefore  5,^,  =  5, 1  1  —   — 


n     Mill)/      ^       K\ 


a^  —  a^^, 


'^'       n        n)  h        \--     --+1      r^nl 


% 

mn 


Ka,Jl-\ 


O^x-^- 


mn 


We  can  thus  estabHsh  our  result  by  induction;  for  we  may 
shew  in  the  manner  just  given  that 


3.^      "-(^-^- 

1-  — 

mn 


and  then  universally  that 


m      tn  V         nj 


785.     We  may  put  our  result  in  the  form 


,                      ma. 
J.  = ' 


i4.(^,_i)(i^ir 


TKEMBLEY.  4:2  O 

Now  there  is  nothing  to  hinder  us  from  supposing  the  intervals 
of  time  to  be  much  shorter  than  a  year ;  thus  n  may  be  a  large 
number,  and  then 

(1 j    =  e''    nearly. 

The  result  thus  agrees  with  that  given  by  Daniel  Bernoulli,  see 
Art.  402  :  for  the  intervals  in  his  theory  may  be  much  shorter  than 
a  year. 

786.  Hitherto  we  have  used  Daniel  Bernoulli's  hypotheses ; 
Trembley  however  proceeds  to  a  more  general  hypothesis.  He 
supposes  that  m  and  7i  are  not  constant,  but  vary  from  year  to 
year ;  so  that  we  may  take  m^  and  oi^  to  denote  their  values  for  the 
x^^  year.  There  is  no  difficulty  in  working  this  hypothesis  by 
Trembley's  method ;  the  results  are  of  course  more  complicated 
than  those  obtained  on  Daniel  Bernoulli's  simpler  hypotheses. 

787.  Trembley  then  compares  the  results  he  obtains  on  his 
general  hypothesis  with  a  table  which  had  been  furnished  by  ob- 
servations at  Berlin  during  the  years  1758 — 1774.  The  comparison 
is  effected  by  a  rude  process  of  approximation.  The  conclusions  he 
arrives  at  are  that  7i  is  very  nearly  constant  for  all  ages,  its  value 
being  somewhat  less  than  6 ;  but  m  varies  considerably,  for  it  be- 
gins by  being  equal  to  6,  and  mounts  up  to  120  at  the  eleventh 
year  of  age,  then  diminishes  to  60  at  the  nineteenth  year  of 
age,  and  mounts  up  again  to  133  at  the  twenty-fifth  year  of  age, 
and  then  diminishes. 

Trembley  also  compares  the  results  he  obtains  on  his  general 
hypothesis  with  another  table  which  had  been  furnished  by  obser- 
vations at  the  Hague.  It  must  be  confessed  that  the  values  of  m 
and  n  deduced  from  this  set  of  observations  differ  very  much  from 
those  deduced  from  the  former  set,  especially  the  values  of  m. 
The  observations  at  Berlin  were  nearly  five  times  as  numerous  as 
those  at  the  Hague,  so  that  they  deserved  more  confidence. 

788.  In  the  volume  for  1804  of  the  Memoires  de  VAcad..., 
Berlin,  which  was  published  in  1807,  there  is  a  note  by  Trem- 
bley himself  on  the  memoir  which  we  have  just  examined. 
This  note  is  entitled  Eclaircissement  relatif  au  Memoire  sur  la 


42G  TREMBLEY. 

mortalite....(i'C.;  it  occurs  on  pages  80 — 82  of  the  mathematical 
portion  of  the  vokime. 

Trembley  corrects  some  misprints  in  the  memoir,  and  he  says  : 

Au  reste,  je  dois  avertir  que  la  metliode  d' approximation  que  j'ai 
donn^e  dans  ce  memoire  comme  un  essai,  en  attendant  que  des  obser- 
vations plus  detaillees  nous  missent  en  etat  de  proceder  avec  plus  de 
regularite,  que  cette  methode,  dis-je,  ne  vaut  absolument  rien,  et  je  dois 
des  excuses  au  public  pour  la  lui  avoir  presentee. 

He  then  shews  how  a  more  accurate  calculation  may  be  made ; 
and  he  says  that  he  has  found  that  the  values  of  n  instead  of 
remaining  nearly  constant  really  varied  enormously. 

789.  The  next  memoir  is  entitled  Essai  sur  la  maniere  de 
trouver  le  teime  general  des  series  r^currentes. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  volume  for  1797  of  the  Me- 
moires  de  V Acad.... Berlin  ;  the  date  of  publication  is  1800,  The 
pages  97 — 105  of  the  memoir  are  devoted  to  the  solution  of  a  pro- 
blem which  had  been  solved  by  Laplace  in  Vol.  vii.  of  the 
Me  moires... par  divers  Savans ;  Trembley  refers  to  Laplace. 

The  problem  is  as  follows  :  Suppose  a  solid  having  n  equal 
faces  numbered  1,  2,  3  ...jy,  required  the  probability  that  in  the 
course  of  n  throws  the  faces  will  appear  in  the  order  1,  2,  8,  ...p. 

This  problem  is  very  nearly  the  same  as  that  of  De  Moivre  on 
the  run  of  luck  ;  see  Art.  325.     Instead  of  the  equation 

'^«+i  =Un+  0--  Un_p)  ha^, 
we  shall  now  have 

^^«+i  =  '^^n  +  (1  —  Wn_")  «^' ;  and  a=-. 

V 

Trembley  solves  the  problem  in  his  usual  incomplete  manner ; 
he  discusses  in  succession  the  cases  in  which  p  =  2,  3,  4 ;  and  then 
he  asssumes  that  the  law  which  holds  in  these  cases  will  hold 
generally. 

790.  The  next  memoir  is  entitled  Ohservations  sur  les  calculs 
relatifs  a  la  dur^e  des  mariages  et  au  nornhre  des  dpoux  suhsistans. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  volume  for  1799 — 1800  of 
the  Memoir es  de  T Acad... Berlin ;  the  date  of  publication  is  1803; 
the  memoir  occupies  pages  110 — 130  of  the  mathematical  portion 
of  the  volume. 


TREMBLEY.  427 

791.  The  memoir  refers  to  that  of  Daniel  Bernoulli  on  the 
same  subject  which  we  have  noticed  in  Art.  412.  Trembley  ob- 
tains results  agreeing  with  those  of  Daniel  Bernoulli  so  far  as  the 
latter  was  rigorous  in  his  investigations ;  but  Trembley  urges  ob- 
jections against  some  of  the  results  obtained  by  the  use  of  the 
infinitesimal  calculus,  and  which  were  only  presented  as  aiDproxi- 
mate  by  Daniel  Bernoulli. 

792.  As  is  usual  with  Trembley,  the  formula  which  occur 
are  not  demonstrated,  but  only  obtained  by  induction  from  some 
simple  cases.  Thus  he  spends  three  pages  in  arriving  at  the  re- 
sult which  we  have  given  in  Art.  410  from  Daniel  Bernoulli ;  he 
examines  in  succession  the  five  most  simple  cases,  for  which 
m  =  1,  2,  3,  4,  5,  and  then  infers  the  general  formula  by  analogy. 

793. .  For  another  example  of  his  formulae  we  take  the  follow- 
ing question.  Suppose  n  men  marry  n  women  at  the  same  time ; 
if  w  out  of  the  2n  die^  required  the  chance  that  m  marriages  are 
dissolved. 

[^ 
We  may  take  m  pairs  out  of  n  in  j ways.     In  each 


7?2 


n  —  in 


of  the  m  pairs  only  one  person  must  die  ;  this  can  happen  in  2'" 
ways.     Thus  the  whole  number  of  cases  favourable  to  the  result 

is  , = —  .     But   the   whole   number   of  cases   is   the   whole 

\m 


n  —  m 


number  of  ways  in  which  77i  persons  out  of  2n  may  die ;  that  is 

\2n  ^  ^ 

.     Hence  the  required  chance  is 


in 


2n  —  7n 

2'"  [^  I  2?i  —  m 


2 II 


n  —  in 


Trembley  spends  two  pages  on  this  problem,  and  then  does 
not  demonstrate  the  result. 

794.  Trembley  makes  some  api^lications  of  his  formulae  to  the 
subject  of  annuities  for  widows.  He  refers  to  a  work  by  Karstens, 
entitled  Theorie  von  Wittwencassen,  Halle,  1784;  and  also  names 
Tetens.     On  the  other  hand,  he  names  Michelsen  as  a  writer  who 


428  TREMBLE  Y. 

had  represented  the  calculations  of  mathematicians  on  such  sub- 
jects as  destitute  of  foundation. 

Trembley  intimates  his  intention  of  continuing  his  investi- 
gations in  another  memoir,  which  I  presume  never  appeared. 

795.  The  next  memoir  is  entitled  Observations  sur  la  metJiode 
de  prendre  les  milieux  entre  les  observations. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  volume  for  1801  of  the 
Memoir es  de  T Acad.  ...  Berlin ;  the  date  of  publication  of  the 
volume  is  1804  :  the  memoir  occupies  pages  29 — 58  of  the  mathe- 
matical portion  of  the  volume. 

796.  The  memoir  commences  thus : 

La  maniere  la  plus  avantagense  de  prendre  les  milieux  entre  les 
observations  a  ete  detaillee  par  de  grands  geometres.  M.  Daniel  Ber- 
noidli,  M.  Lambert,  M.  de  la  Place,  M.  de  la  Grange  s'en  sont  occupes. 
Le  dernier  a  donne  la-dessus  un  tres-beau  memoire  dans  le  Tome  v.  des 
Memoires  de  Turin.  II  a  employe  pour  cela  le  calcul  integral.  Mon 
dessein  dans  ce  memoire  est  de  montrer  comment  on  peut  parvenir  aux 
niemes  resultats  par  un  simple  usage  de  la  doctrine  des  combinaisons. 

797.  The  preceding  extract  shews  the  object  of  the  memoir. 
We  observe  however  that  although  Lagrange  does  employ  the 
Integral  Calculus,  yet  it  is  only  in  the  latter  part  of  his  memoir, 
on  wdiich  Trembley  does  not  touch ;  see  Arts.  570 — 575.  In  the 
other  portions  of  his  memoir,  Lagrange  uses  the  Differential  Cal- 
culus ;  but  it  was  quite  unnecessary  for  him  to  do  so ;  see 
Art.  564. 

Trembley's  memoir  appears  to  be  of  no  value  whatever.  The 
method  is  laborious,  obscure,  and  imperfect,  while  Lagrange's  is 
simple,  clear,  and  decisive.  Trembley  begins  with  De  Moivre's 
problem,  quoting  from  him ;  see  Art.  149.  He  considers  De 
Moivre's  demonstration  indirect  and  gives  another.  Trembley's 
demonstration  occupies  eight  pages,  and  a  reader  would  probably 
find  it  necessary  to  fill  up  many  parts  with  more  detail,  if  he  were 
scrupulous  about  exactness. 

After  discussing  De  Moivre's  problem  in  this  manner,  Trem- 
bley proceeds  to  inflict  similar  treatment  on  Lagrange's  problems. 

We  may  remark  that  Trembley   copies  a  formula  from  La- 


TREMBLEY.  4*29 

grange   with  all  tlie  misprints  or  errors  which  it  involves;   see 
Art.  567. 

798.  The  last  memoir  by  Trembley  is  entitled  Observations 
sur  le  calcul  cVun  Jeu  de  hasard. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  volume  for  1802  of  the 
Memoir es  de  V Acad.  ...  Berlin ;  the  date  of  publication  is  180-i  : 
the  memoir  occupies  pages  86 — 102  of  the  mathematical  portion 
of  the  volume. 

799.  The  game  considered  is  that  of  Her,  which  gave  rise  to 
a  dispute  between  Nicolas  Bernoulli  and  others ;  see  Art.  187. 
Trembley  refers  to  the  dispute. 

Trembley  investigates  fully  the  chance  of  Paul  for  every  case 
that  can  occur,  and  more  briefly  the  chance  of  Peter.  He  states 
his  conclusion  thus : 

...M.  de  Montmort  et  ses  amis  concluoient  de  la  centre  Nicolas 
Bernoulli,  que  ce  cas  6toit  insoluble,  car  disoient-ils,  si  Paul  sait  que 
Pierre  se  tient  au  huit,  il  cliangera  an  sept,  mais  Pierre  venant  k  savoir 
que  Paul  change  au  sept,  changera  au  huit,  ce  qui  fait  un  cercle  vicieux. 
Mais  il  resulte  seulement  de  la  que  chacun  sera  perjDetuellement  dans 
I'incertitude  sur  la  maniere  de  jouer  de  son  adversaire;  des  lors  il  con- 
viendra  a  Paul  de  changer  au  sept  dans  un  coup  donne,  mais  il  ne 
pourroit  suivre  constamment  ce  sjsteme  plusieurs  coups  de  suite.  II 
conviendra  de  meme  a  Pierre  de  changer  au  huit  dans  un  coup  donn6, 
sans  pouvoir  le  faire  plusieurs  coups  de  suite,  ce  qui  s'accorde  avec  les 
conclusions  de  M.  Nicolas  Bernoulli  contre  celles  de  M.  de  Montmort. 

800.  It  is  hardly  correct  to  say  that  the  conclusion  here 
obtained  agrees  with  that  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli  against  that  of 
Montmort.  The  opponents  of  Nicolas  Bernoulli  seem  only  to 
have  asserted  that  it  was  impossible  to  say  on  which  rule  Paul 
should  uniformly  act,  and  this  Trembley  allows. 

801.  In  Trembley's  investigation  of  the  chance  of  Peter,  he 
considers  this  chance  at  the  epoch  before  Paul  has  made  his  choice 
ivhether  he  will  exchange  or  not.  But  this  is  of  little  value  for 
Peter  himself ;  Peter  would  want  to  know  how  to  act  under  cer- 
tain circumstances,  and  before  he  acted  he  would  know  whether 
Paul  retained  the  card  he  obtained  at  first  or  compelled  an  ex- 


480  TREMBLEY. 

change.     Hence  Trembley's  investigation  of  Peter's  chance  differs 
from  the  method  which  we  have  exemplified  in  Art.  189. 

802.  Trembley  makes  an  attemjDt  to  solve  the  problem  of 
Her  for  three  players ;  but  his  solution  is  quite  unsound.  Sup- 
pose there  are  three  players,  Paul,  James,  and  Peter.  Trembley 
considers  that  the  chances  of  Paul  and  James  are  in  the  propor- 
tion of  the  chance  of  the  first  and  second  players  when  there  are 
only  two  players  ;  and  he  denotes  these  chances  by  x  and  y.  He 
takes  aj  to  ?/  as  8496  to  8079 ;  but  these  numbers  are  of  no  con- 
sequence for  our  purpose.  He  supposes  that  the  chances  of  James 
and  Peter  are  also  in  the  same  proportion.  This  would  not  be 
quite  accurate,  because  when  James  is  estimating  his  chance  with 
respect  to  Peter  he  would  have  some  knowledge  of  Paul's  card ; 
whereas  in  the  case  of  Paul  and  James,  the  former  had  no  know- 
ledge of  any  other  card  than  his  own  to  guide  him  in  retaining  or 
exchanging. 

But  this  is  only  a  minute  point.     Trembley's  error  is  in  the 

next  step.     He  considers  that  is  the  chance  that  Paul  will 

x  +  y 

beat  James,  and  that    —^ —  is  the  chance  that  Peter  will  beat 

x-\-y 

James ;  he  infers  that  -. — ^-^  is  the  chance  that  both  Paul  and 

{x-^yf 

Peter  will  beat  James,  so  that  James  will  be  thrown  out  at  the 
first  trial.     This  is  false:  the  game   is   so    constructed  that  the 

players  are  nearly  on  the  same  footing,  so  that  -  is  very  nearly 

o 

the  chance  that  a  given  player  will  be  excluded  at  the  first  trial. 

1 

Trembley's  solution  would  give  -  as  the  chance  that  James  will 

be  excluded  ii  x=y)  whereas  -^  should  then  be  the  value. 

X  11 

The  error  arises  from  the  fact  that  and  — '- do  not 

x-\-  y  ^  +  y 

here  represent  independent  chances ;  of  course  if  Paul  has  a  higher 

card  than  James,  this  alone  affords  presumption  that  James  will 

rather  have  a  card  inferior  to  that  of  Peter  than  superior.     This 

error  at  the  beginning  vitiates  Trembley's  solution. 


TREMBLE  Y.  431 

803.  As  a  subsidiary  part  of  his  solution  Trembley  gives 
a  tedious  numerical  investigation  which  might  be  easily  spared. 
He  wishes  to  shew  that  supposing  James  to  have  a  higher  card 
than  both  Peter  and  Paul,  it  is  an  even  chance  whether  Peter 
or  Paul  is  excluded.  He  might  have  proceeded  thus,  which  will 
be  easily  intelligible  to  a  person  who  reads  the  description  of  the 
game  in  Montmort,  pages  278,  279  : 

Let  n  denote  the  number  of  James's  card. 

I.  Suppose  n  —  r  and  n  —  s  the  other  two  cards ;  where  r  and 
s  are  positive  integers  and  different.  Then  either  Paul  or  Peter 
may  have  the  lower  of  the  two  n  —  r  and  n  —  s\  that  is,  there  are 
as  many  cases  favourable  to  one  as  the  other. 

II.  Peter's  card  may  also  be  n\  then  Paul's  must  be  1,  or 
2,  or  3, ...  or  ?i  —  1.     Here  are  n  —  1  cases  favourable  to  Peter. 

III.  Peter  and  Paul  may  both  have  a  card  with  the  same 
mark  n  —  r\  this  will  give  n  —  1  cases  favourable  to  Paul. 

Thus  II.  and  III.  balance. 


CHAPTER   XIX. 


MISCELLANEOUS    INVESTIGATIONS 
Between  the  Years  1780  and  1800. 


804.  The  present  Chapter  will  contain  notices  of  various 
contributions  to  our  subject  wliicli  were  made  between  the  years 
1750  and  1780. 

805.  We  have  first  to  mention  two  memoirs  by  Prevost,  en- 
titled, Sur  les  principes  de  la  Theorie  des  gains  fortuits. 

The  first  memoir  is  in  the  volume  for  1780  of  the  Nouveaux 
Memoires ..,  Berlin ;  the  date  of  publication  is  1782:  the  memoir 
occupies  pages  430 — 472.  The  second  memoir  is  in  the  volume 
for  1781 ;  the  date  of  publication  is  1783 :  the  memoir  occupies 
pages  463 — 472.  Prevost  professes  to  criticise  the  account  of  the 
elementary  principles  of  the  subject  given  by  James  Bernoulli, 
Huygens,  and  De  Moivre.  It  does  not  seem  that  the  memoirs 
present  anything  of  value  or  importance  ;  see  Art.  103. 

806.  We  have  next  to  notice  a  memoir  by  Borda,  entitled 
Memoir e  sur  les  Elections  an  Scrutin. 

This  is  in  the  Hist....de  V Acad.... Paris  for  1781  ;  the  date  of 
publication  is  1784  :  the  memoir  occupies  pages  657 — QQo. 

This  memoir  is  not  connected  with  Probability,  but  we  notice 
it  because  the  subject  is  considered  at  great  length  by  Condorcet, 
who  refers  to  Borda's  view ;  see  Art.  719. 


BORDA.  433 

Borda  observes  that  the  ordinary  mode  of  election  is  liable  to 
error.  Suppose,  for  example,  that  there  are  21  voters,  out  of 
whom  8  vote  for  A,  7  for  B,  and  6  for  (7;  then  A  is  elected.  But 
it  is  possible  that  the  7  who  voted  for  B  and  the  6  who  voted 
for  C  may  agree  in  considering  A  as  the  worst  of  the  three  can- 
didates, although  they  differ  about  the  merits  of  B  and  G.  In  such 
a  case  there  are  8  voters  for  A  and  13  against  him  out  of  the 
21  voters ;  and  so  Borda  considers  that  A  ought  not  to  be  elected. 
In  fact  in  this  case  if  there  were  only  A  and  B  as  candidates,  or 
only  A  and  C  as  candidates,  A  would  lose ;  he  gains  because  he 
is  opposed  by  two  men  who  are  both  better  than  himself. 

Borda  suggests  that  each  voter  should  arrange  the  candidates 
in  what  he  thinks  the  order  of  merit.  Then  in  collecting  the 
results  w^e  may  assign  to  a  candidate  a  marks  for  each  lowest 
place,  a  +  h  marks  for  each  next  ^Dlace,  a  +  2b  marks  for  each  next 
place,  and  so  on  if  there  are  more  than  three  candidates.  Suppose 
for  example  that  there  are  three  candidates,  and  that  one  of  them 
is  first  in  the  lists  of  6  voters,  second  in  the  lists  of  10  voters,  and 
third  in  the  lists  of  5  voters ;  then  his  aggregate  merit  is  ex- 
pressed by  6  {a  +  2h)  +  10  {a  +  h)  +  oa,  that  is  by  21a  +  225.  It 
is  indifferent  what  proportion  w^e  establish  between  a  and  h,  be- 
cause in  the  aggregate  merit  of  each  candidate  the  coefficient  of  a 
will  be  the  whole  number  of  voters. 

Condorcet  objects  to  Borda's  method,  and  he  gives  the  follow- 
ing example.  Let  there  be  three  candidates.  A,  B,  and  C\  and 
suppose  81  voters.  Suppose  that  the  order  ABC  is  adopted  by 
30  voters,  the  order  A  CB  by  1,  the  order  CAB  by  10,  the  order 
BAG  hy  29,  the  order  BGA  by  10,  and  the  order  GBA  by  1.  In 
this  case  B  is  to  be  elected  on  Borda's  method,  for  his  aggTegate 
merit  is  ex^Dressed  by  81a +  1095,  while  that  of  ^  is  expressed 
by  81a +  1015,  and  that  of  G  by  81a +  335.  Condorcet  decides 
that  A  ought  to  be  elected ;  for  the  proposition  A  is  better  than  B 
is  affirmed  by  30  +  1  +  10  voters,  w^hile  the  proposition  B  is  better 
than  A  is  affirmed  by  29  +  10  +  1  voters,  so  that  A  has  the  ad- 
vantage over  B  in  the  ratio  of  41  to  40. 

Thus  suppose  a  voter  to  adopt  the  order  ABG;  then  Condorcet 
considers  him  to  affirm  with  equal  emphasis  the  three  propositions 
A  is  better  than  B,  B  is  better  than  C,  A  is  better  than  0;  but 

28 


43i  MALFATTI. 

Borda  considers  him  to  affirm  the  first  two  with  equal  emphasis, 
and  the  last  with  double  emphasis.  See  Condorcet's  Discours 
Preliminaire,  page  CLXXVii,  Laplace,  Theorie . . .  des  Froh.  page  274. 

807.  We  have  next  to  notice  a  memoir  by  Malfatti,  entitled 
Esame  Critico  di  un  Prohlema  di  pjvhahilita  del  Sig.  Baniele 
Bernoulli,  e  soluzione  d'un  cdtro  Prohlema  analogo  al  Bermdliano. 
Del  Sig.  Gio:  Francesco  Malfatti  Professore  di  Matematica  nell' 
Universita  di  Ferrara. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  Memorie  di  Matematica  e 
Fisica  delta  Societa  Italiana,  Tomo  i.  1782  ;  the  memoir  occupies 
pages  768 — 824.  The  problem  is  that  which  we  have  noticed  in 
Art.  416.  Malfatti  considers  the  solution  of  the  problem  about 
the  balls  to  be  erroneous,  and  that  this  problem  is  essentially 
different  from  that  about  the  fluids  which  Daniel  Bernoulli  used 
to  illustrate  the  former ;  see  Art.  420.  Malfatti  restricts  himself 
to  the  case  of  two  urns. 

Malfatti  in  fact  says  that  the  problem  ought  to  be  solved  by 
an  exact  comparison  of  the  numbers  of  the  various  cases  which 
can  arise,  and  not  by  the  use  of  such  equations  as  we  have  given 
in  Art.  417,  which  are  only  probably  true ;  this  of  course  is  quite 
correct,  but  it  does  not  invalidate  Daniel  Bernoulli's  process  for 
its  own  object. 

Let  us  take  a  single  case.  SujDpose  that  originally  there  are  two 
white  balls  in  A  and  two  black  balls  in  B ;  required  the  probable 
state  of  the  urn  A  after  x  of  Daniel  Bernoulli's  operations  have 
been  performed.  Let  u^  denote  the  probability  that  there  are 
two  black  balls  in  A  ;  v^  the  probability  that  there  is  one  black 
ball  and  one  white  one,  and  therefore  1-u^-v^  the  probability 
that  there  are  two  white  balls. 

808.  We  will  first  give  a  Lemma  of  Malfatti's.  Suppose  there 
tiren-p  white  balls  in  A,  and  therefore p  black  balls ;  then  there 
are  n  —p  black  balls  in  B  and  p  white  balls.  Let  one  of  Daniel 
Bernoulli's  operations  be  performed,  and  let  us  find  the  number 
of  cases  in  which  each  possible  event  can  happen.  There  are  w^ 
cases  altogether,  for  any  ball  can  be  taken  from  A  and  any  ball 
from  B.  Now  there  are  three  possible  events  ;  for  after  the  opera- 
tion A  may  contain  n—p-^\  white  balls,  or  n—p,  or  n—p  —  \. 


MALFATTI.  435 

For  the  first  event  a  black  ball  must  be  taken  from  A  and  a  white 
ball  from  B ;  the  number  of  cases  is  p\  For  the  second  event  a 
black  ball  must  be  taken  from  A  and  a  black  one  from  B,  or  else 
a  white  one  from  A  and  a  white  one  from  B ;  the  number  of  cases 
is  2p{7i—j)).  For  the  third  event  a  white  ball  must  be  taken 
from   A    and   a  black   ball   from  B;   the    number   of    cases   is 

{n  —]pf- 

It  is  obvious  that 

as  should  be  the  case. 

809.     Now  returning  to  the  problem  in  Art.  807  it  will  be 
easy  to  form  the  follov/ing  equations : 

1 

1 

Integrating  these  equations  and  determining  the  constant  by 
the  condition  that  ^^^  =  1,  we  obtain 

2  f        (- 1)-)  1  j        (_  1)-) 

Daniel  Bernoulli's  general  result  for  the  probable  number  of 
white  balls  in  A  after  x  trials  if  there  were  7i  originally  would  be 

Thus  supposing  x  is  infinite  Daniel  Bernoulli  finds  that  the 

71/ 

probable  number  is  ^ .     This  is  not  inconsistent  with  our  result ; 

2  1 

for  w^e  have   when   x  is  infinite   Vy,  =  -^y    ^^  =  t^ >    ^iid   therefore 

o  u 

1 

\  —  Vy,  —  u^—-,  so  that  the  case  of  one  white  ball  and  one  black 

ball  is  the  most  probable. 


810.     Malfatti  advances  an  objection  against  Daniel  Bernoulli's 

obtain 
28—2 


result  which  seems  of  no  weight.     Daniel  Bernoulli  obtains   as 


436  MALFATTI. 

we  see  ^  for  the  probable  number  of  white  balls  in  A  after  an 

infinite  number  of  operations.  Now  Malfatti  makes  Daniel  Ber- 
noulli's statement  imply  conversely  that  it  will  require  an  infinite 

71/ 

number  of  trials  before  the  result  ^  will  probably  be  reached. 

But  Daniel  Bernoulli  himself  does  not  state  or  imply  this  con- 
verse, so  that  Malfatti  is  merely  criticising  a  misapprehension  of 
his  own. 

811.  Malfatti  himself  gives  a  result  equivalent  to  our  value 
of  u^  in  Art.  809  ;  he  does  not  obtain  it  in  the  way  we  use,  but 
by  induction  founded  on  examination  of  successive  cases,  and  not 
demonstrated  generally. 

812.  The  problem  which  Malfatti  proposes  to  solve  and  which 
he  considers  analogous  to  Daniel  Bernoulli's  is  the  following. 
Let  r  be  zero  or  any  given  integer  not  greater  than  n :  required 
to  determine  the  probability  that  in  x  operations  the  event  will 
never  occur  of  having  just  n  —  r  white  balls  in  A.  This  he  treats 
in  a  most  laborious  way ;  he  supposes  r  =  2,  3,  4,  5  in  succession, 
and  obtains  the  results.  He  extracts  by  inspection  certain  laws 
from  these  results  which  he  assumes  will  hold  for  all  the  other 
values  of  r  between  6  and  n  inclusive.  The  cases  r  —  0,  and  r  =  1, 
require  special  treatment. 

Thus  the  results  are  not  demonstrated,  though  perhaps  little 
doubt  of  their  exactness  would  remain  in  the  mind  of  a  student. 
The  patience  and  acuteness  which  must  have  been  required  to 
extract  the  laws  will  secure  high  admiration  for  Malfatti. 

813.  We  will  give  one  specimen  of  the  results  which  Malfatti 
obtains,  though  we  shall  adopt  an  exact  method  instead  of  his  in- 
duction from  particular  cases. 

Required  the  probability  that  in  x  trials  the  number  ?i  —  2  of 
white  balls  will  never  occur  in  A.  Let  (/>  {x,  n)  represent  the  whole 
number  of  favourable  cases  in  x  trials  which  end  with  7i  white  balls 
in  ^ ;  let  0  (ic,  n  —  1)  be  the  whole  number  of  favourable  cases 
which  end  with  n  —  1  white  balls  in  A.     There  is  no  other  class  of 


MALFATTI.  437 

favourable  cases ;  by  favourable  cases  we  mean  cases  of  non-occur- 
rence o{  n  —  2  white  balls. 

By  aid  of  the  Lemma  in  Art.  808  the  following  equations  are 
immediately  established, 

</)  (ic  +  1,  ??)  =  (f)  (x,  n  -  1), 
<f>  (x-\-l,  n  —  l)  —  '}f<j>  {x,  n)  +  2  (?2  —  1)  ^  (x,  n  —  1). 

By  aid  of  the  first  the  second  becomes 

<f)[x+l,n-l)=  n^cf)  {x  -  1,  n  -  1)  +  2  {n  -1)  (f)  (x,  n  -  1). 

Thus  denoting  (^  (x,  n  —  1)  by  u^  we  have 

«x-+i  =  i^u^_^  +  2  (?i  -  1)  u^. 

This  shews  that  ii^  is  of  the  form  Aa^  +  B/S'^  where  a  and  /3  are 
the  roots  of  the  quadratic 

From  the  first  of  the  above  equations  we  see  that  </)  (x  +  1,  n) 
is  of  the  same /or??i  as  ^  {x,  n  —  1);  thus  finally  we  have 

</)  (ic,  w)  +  </)  (x,  n  -  1)  =  arj."  +  h/S", 

Avhere  a  and  h  are  constants.  The  required  probability  is  found  by 
dividing  by  the  whole  number  of  cases,  that  is  by  ?i^*  Thus  we 
obtain 

n 

We  must  determine  the  constants  a  and  h  by  special  examina- 
tion of  the  first  and  second  operations.  After  the  first  oj^eration 
we  must  have  m  -  1  white  balls  and  one  black  ball  in  A  ;  all  the 
cases  are  favourable  ;  this  will  give 

aa  +  h^  =  n^. 
Similarly  we  get 

for  tlie  second  operation  must  either  give  n  white  balls  in  A,  or 
n-1,  or  71-2;  and  the  first  and  second  cases  are  favourable. 

Thus  a  and  b  become  known,  and  the  problem  is  completely 
solved. 


438  BICQUILLEY. 

814.  We  will  briefly  indicate  the  steps  for  the  solution  of  the 
problem  in  which  we  require  the  probability  that  n  —  S  white  balls 
shall  never  occur  in  A. 

Let  (j)  {oc,  n),  </>  {x,  n  —  1),  (/)  [x,  n  —  2)  represent  the  number  of 
favourable  cases  in  x  trials,  where  the  final  number  of  white  balls 
in  A  is  01,  n  —  1,  n—  2,  respectively. 

Then  we  have  the  following  equations 

(f>  (x  +  1,  n)  =(j)  (x,  n  —  V), 
(f){x+l,n-l)=  ?i'</)  (x,  n)  +  2{n-l)  ^  {x,  ?j  -  1)  +  4(/)  {x,  n  -  2), 
<j>{x^l,n-2)  =  (n-rf<^{x,  n-  1)  +  4  {ii  -  2)  ^  i^x,  7i-2). 

If  we  denote  </>  (x,  n  —  2)  by  u^  we  shall  arrive  by  elimination  at 
the  equation 

w^+3  ~  {Qn  -  10)  u^^^  +  (Sti'  -  16?i  + 12)  ii^^^  +  W  (?i  -  2)  u^  =  0. 

Then  it  will  be  seen  that  <f>(x,  n  —  V)  and  0  (x,  n)  will  be  ex- 
pressions of  the  same  form  as  </>  (x,  n  —  2).  Thus  the  whole  num- 
ber of  favourable  cases  will  be  aa""'  +  h^''  +  07""',  where  a,  h,  c  are 
arbitrary  constants,  and  a,  ft  7  are  the  roots  of 

z'  -  {6n  -  10)  z''  +  (Sn'  -  16?i  +  12)  z  +  W  (n-2)  =  0. 

815.  A  work  on  our  subject  was  published  by  Bicquilley,  en- 
titled Die  Calcul  des  Prohabilites.  Par  C.  F.  de  Bicquilley,  Garde- 
du-Corps  du  Roi.     1783. 

This  work  is  of  small  octavo  size,  and  contains  a  preface  of 
three  pages,  the  Privilege  du  Roi,  and  a  table  of  contents ;  then 
164  pages  of  text  with  a  plate. 

According  to  the  Catalogues  of  Booksellers  there  is  a  second 
edition  published  in  1805  which  I  have  not  seen. 

816.  The  author's  object  is  stated  in  the  following  sentence 
from  the  Preface  : 

La  theorie  des  Prohabilites  ebaucliee  par  des  Geometres  celebres  m'a 
paru  susceptible  d'etre  approfondee,  et  de  faire  j)artie  de  renseignement 
^lementaire  :  j'ai  pense  qu'un  traite  ne  seroit  point  indigne  d'etre  offert 
au  public,  qui  pourroit  enriclier  de  nouvelles  verites  cette  matiere  inte- 
ressante,  et  la  mettre  a  la  portee  du  plus  grand  nombre  des  lecteurs. 


BICQUILLEY.  439 

The  choice  of  matter  seems  rather  unsuitable  for  an  elementary 
work  on  the  Theory  of  Probability. 

817.  Pages  1 — 15  contain  the  definitions  and  fundamental 
principles.  Pages  15 — 25  contain  an  account  of  Figurate  numbers. 
Passes  26 — 39  contain  various  theorems  which  we  should  now 
describe  as  examples  of  the  Theory  of  Combinations.  Pages  40 — 80 
contain  a  number  of  theorems  which  amount  to  little  more  than 
easy  developments  of  one  fundamental  theorem,  namely  that  which 
we  have  given  in  Art.  281,  supposing  ^  =  0. 

818.  Pages  81 — 110  may  be  said  to  amount  to  the  following 

theorem  and  its  consequences  :  if  the   chance  of  an  event  at  a 

single  trial  be  ^  the  chance  that  it  will  occur  m  times  and  fail  n 

m  +  7i 
times  in  m-{-7i  trials  is  i^'"  0-  ~PT' 


m    n 


Here  we  may  notice  one  problem  which  is  of  interest.  Sup- 
pose that  at  every  trial  we  must  have  either  an  event  P  alone,  oi 
an  event  Q  alone,  or  both  P  and  Q,  or  neither  P  nor  Q,  Let  p 
denote  the  chance  of  P  alone,  q  the  chance  of  Q  alone,  t  the 
chance  of  both  P  and  Q  :  then  1  —  ^  —  ^  —  ^  is  the  chance  of  nei- 
ther P  nor  Q ;  we  will  denote  this  by  tc.  Various  problems  may 
then  be  projDOsed ;  Bicquilley  considers  the  following :  required 
the  chance  that  in  fi  trials  P  will  happen  exactly  m  times,  and  Q 
exactly  n  times. 

I.  Suppose  P  and  Q  do  not  happen  together  in  any  case. 
Then  we  have  P  happening  m  times,  Q  happening  7i  times,  and 
neither  P  nor  Q  happening  (m  —  m  —  n  times.  The  corresponding 
chance  is 


I  m  1  n    fi  —  771  —  n 


f^q^^W 


m  -  n 


II.  Suppose  that  P  and  Q  happen  together  once.  Then  we 
have  also  P  happening  m  —  1  times,  Q  happening  ?i  —  1  times,  and 
neither  P  nor  Q  happening  /i,  -  m  -  /i  +  1  times.    The  correspond- 


ing chance  is 


m  —  1    71  —  1    ^6  —  1)1  —  u-r^ 


4i0  BICQUILLEY. 

III.     Suppose  that  P  and  Q  happen  together  tivice.     Tlie  cor- 
responding chance  is 


r"  ..w._f?  _n_5  42,.u.-m-n  +  2 


[2  I  m  -  2  I  ?i-2  I  ^  -  9??  -  ?2  +  2 
And  so  on. 

819.  As  another  example  of  the  hind  of  problem  noticed  in 
the  preceding  Article,  we  may  require  the  cliance  that  in  \l  trials  P 
and  Q  shall  each  happen  at  least  once.     The  required  chance  is 

1  _  (1  _^;  _  ^)^  _  (1  _  ^  _  Q/^  +  (1  -^  -  5^  -  ty. 

See  also  Algehra,  Chapter  LVI. 

820.  Pages  111 — 133  contain  the  solution  of  some  examples. 
Two  of  them  are  borrowed  from  Buffon,  namely  those  which  we 
have  noticed  in  Art.  649,  and  in  the  beginning  of  Art.  650. 

One  of  Bicquilley's  examples  may  be  given.  Suppose  p  and  q 
to  denote  respectively  the  chances  of  the  happening  and  failing  of 
an  event  in  a  single  trial.  A  pla3^er  lays  a  wager  of  a  to  &  that  the 
event  will  happen  ;  if  the  event  does  not  happen  he  repeats  the 
wager,  making  the  stakes  ra  to  rh ;  if  the  event  fails  again  he 
repeats  the  wager,  making  the  stakes  r'^a  to  r^5  ;  and  so  on.  If  the 
player  is  allowed  to  do  this  for  a  series  of  n  games,  required  his 
advantage  or  disadvantage. 

The  player's  disadvantage  is 

This  is  easily  shewn.  For  qa  ~])h  is  obviously  the  player's  dis- 
advantage at  the  first  trial.  Suppose  the  event  fails  at  the  first 
trial,  of  which  the  chance  is  q  ;  then  the  wager  is  renewed  ;  and 
the  disadvantage  for  that  trial  is  qar  —  ph\  Similarly  (f  is  the 
chance  that  the  event  will  fail  twice  in  succession ;  then  the  wager 
is  renewed,  and  the  disadvantage  is  qar^—pbr^.  And  so  on.  If 
then  qa  is  greater  than  ph  the  disadvantage  is  j)ositive  and  in- 
creases with  the  number  of  games. 

Bicquilley   takes   the    particular    case   in   which    a  =  1,    and 

5  +  1      . 

^  =  — -J — ;  his  solution  is  less  simple  than  that  which  we  have 


ENCYCLOPEDIE  Ml^THODIQUE.  44?1 

given.  The  object  of  the  problem  is  to  shew  to  a  gambler,  by  an 
example,  that  if  a  wager  is  really  unfavourable  to  him  he  suffers 
still  more  by  increasing  his  stake  while  the  same  proportion  is 
maintained  between  his  stake  and  that  of  his  adversary. 

821.  Pages  134 — 149  relate  to  the  evaluation  of  probability 
from   experience    or   observation.     If  an  event  has  happened  m 

times  and  failed  n  times  the  book  directs  us  to  take  — - —  as  its 

m-\-  n 

chance  in  a  single  trial. 

822.  Pages  150 — 164  relate  to  the  evaluation  of  probability 
from  testimony.  Bicquilley  adopts  the  method  which  we  have 
exhibited  in  Art.  91.  Another  of  his  peculiarities  is  the  following. 
Suppose  from  our  own  experience,  independent  of  testimony,  we 
assign  the  probability  P  to  an  event,  and  suppose  that  a  witness 
whose  probability  is  2^  offers  his  evidence  to  the  event,  Bicquilley 
takes  for  the  resulting  probability  P+  (1  —  P)  Pp,  and  not  as  we 
might  have  expected  from  him  P  +  (1  —  P)  ^.  He  says  that  the 
reliance  which  we  place  on  a  witness  is  proportional  to  our  own 
previous  estimate  of  the  probability  of  the  event  to  which  he 
testifies. 

823.  We  will  now  notice  the  matter  bearing  on  our  subject 
which  is  contained  in  the  Encyclopedie  Methodique;  the  mathema- 
tical portion  of  this  work  forms  three  quarto  volumes  which  are 
dated  respectively  1784,  1785,  1789. 

Absent  This  article  is  partly  due  to  Condorcet :  he  applies 
the  Theory  of  Probability  to  determine  when  a  man  has  been  ab- 
sent long  enough  to  justify  the  division  of  his  property  among  his 
heirs,  and  also  to  determine  the  portions  which  ought  to  be  assigned 
to  the  different  claimants. 

Assurances.     This  article  contains  nothing  remarkable. 

ProhoMlite.  The  article  from  the  original  Encyclopedie  is  re- 
peated :  see  Art.  467.  This  is  followed  by  another  article  under 
the  same  title,  which  professes  to  give  the  general  principles  of 
the  subject.  The  article  has  not  Condorcet's  signature  formally 
attached  to  it ;  but  its  last  sentence  shews  that  he  was  the  author. 
It  may  be  described  as  an  outline  of  Condorcet's  own  writings  on 


442  ENCYCLOPEDIE   METHODIQUE. 

the  subject,  but  from  its  brevity  it  would  be  far  less  intelligible 
than  even  those  writings. 

Substitutions.  Condorcet  maintains  that  a  State  has  the  autho- 
rity to  change  the  laws  of  succession  to  property ;  but  when  such 
changes  are  made  the  rights  which  existed  under  the  old  laws 
should  be  valued  and  compensation  made  for  them.  In  this  article 
Condorcet  professes  to  estimate  the  amount  of  compensation.  The 
formulae  however  are  printed  in  such  an  obscure  and  repulsive 
manner  that  it  would  be  very  difficult  to  determine  whether  they 
are  correct ;  and  certainly  the  attempt  to  examine  them  would  be 
a  waste  of  time  and  labour. 

824.  It  should  be  observed  that  in  the  Encydopedie  Metlio- 
dique  various  threats  are  uttered  which  are  never  carried  into 
execution.  Thus  in  the  article  Assurances  we  are  referred  to 
Evenemens  and  to  Societe ;  and  in  the  article  Prohabilite  we  are 
referred  to  Verite  and  to  Votans.  Any  person  who  is  acquainted 
with  Condorcet's  writings  will  consider  it  fortunate  that  no  articles 
are  to  be  found  under  the  titles  here  named. 

825.  The  only  important  article  connected  with  our  subject 
in  the  Encydopedie  Metliodique  is  that  under  the  title  Milieu, 
which  we  will  now  proceed  to  notice.  The  article  is  by  John 
Bernoulli,  the  same  person,  we  presume,  whom  we  have  noticed 
in  Arts.  598  and  624. 

The  article  gives  an  account  of  two  memoirs  which  it  asserts 
had  not  then  been  printed.     The  article  says  : 

Le  premier  memoire  dont  je  me  propose  de  doiiner  I'extrait,  est  un 
petit  ecrit  latin  de  M.  Daniel  Bernoulli,  qu'il  me  communiqua,  en 
1769,  et  qu'il  gardoit  depuis  long-tems  parmi  ses  manuscrits  dans  le 
dessein  sans  doute  de  I'ctendre  davantage.  II  a  pour  titre  :  Dijudicatio 
niaxime  j^'^ohahilis  plurium  ohservationimi  discrepmitiu^n ;  atque  verisi- 
niillima  inductio  inde  formanda. 

The  title  is  the  same  as  that  of  the  memoir  which  we  have 
noticed  in  Art.  424 ;  but  this  article  Milieu  gives  an  account  of 
the  memoir  which  does  not  correspond  with  what  we  find  in  the 
Acta  Acad..,.Petrop.,  so  we  conclude  that  Daniel  Bernoulli  modi- 
fied his  memoir  before  publishing  it. 


ENCYCLOPEDIE   METHODIQUE.  443 

The  following  is  the  method  given  in  the  article  Milieu.  Let 
the  numerical  results  of  discordant  observations  be  set  off  as 
abscissae  from  a  fixed  point ;  draw  ordinates  to  represent  the  pro- 
babilities of  the  various  observations ;  trace  a  curve  through  the 
extremities  of  these  ordinates  and  take  the  abscissa  of  the  centre 
of  gravity  of  the  area  of  the  curve  as  the  correct  value  of  the 
element  sought.  The  probabilities  are  to  be  represented  by  the 
ordinates  of  a  certain  semi-ellipse  or  semicircle.  The  article  says 
that  to  determine  analytically  the  centre  of  the  semicircle  would 
be  very  difficult,  because  we  arrive  at  an  equation  which  is  almost 
unmanageable ;  accordingly  a  method  of  approximation  is  pro- 
posed. First  take  for  the  centre  the  point  corresponding  to  the 
mean  of  all  the  observations;  and  determine  the  centre  of  gravity 
of  the  area  corresponding  to  the  observations ;  take  this  point 
as  a  new  centre  of  a  semicircle,  and  repeat  the  operation ;  and 
so  on,  until  the  centre  of  gravity  obtained  corresponds  with 
the  centre  of  the  respective  semicircle.  The  magnitude  of  the 
radius  of  the  semicircle  must  be  assigned  arbitrarily  by  the  cal- 
culator. 

This  is  ingenious,  but  of  course  there  is  no  evidence  that  w^e 
thus  obtain  a  result  which  is  specially  trustworthy. 

The  other  memoir  which  is  noticed,  in  this  article  Milieu  is 
that  by  Lagrange,  published  in  the  Miscellanea  Taurinensia ;  see 
Art.  boQ.  It  is  strange  that  the  memoirs  by  Daniel  Bernoulli 
and  Lagrange  should  be  asserted  to  be  unprinted  in  1785,  when 
Daniel  Bernoulli  had  published  a  memoir  with  the  same  title  in 
the  Acta  Acad....Petrop.  for  1777,  and  Lagrange's  memoir  was 
published  in  the  Miscellanea  Taurinensia  for  1770 — 1773.  The 
date  of  publication  of  the  last  volume  is  not  given,  but  that  it 
was  prior  to  1777  w^e  may  infer  from  a  memoir  by  Euler;  see 
Art.  447. 

826.  We  will  now  notice  the  portions  of  the  Encyclopedie 
Methodique  which  relate  to  games  of  chance.  The  three  volumes 
which  we  have  mentioned  in  Ai't.  817  contain  articles  on  various 
games  ;  they  do  not  give  mathematical  investigations,  with  a  slight 
exception  in  the  case  of  Bassette :  see  Art.  467.  The  commence- 
ment of  the  article  Breland  is  amusing:    il   se  joue  a   tant   de 


444?  ENCYCLOPEDIE   METHODIQUE. 

jjersonnes  que  Von  veut:  mais  il  n^est  beau,  c'est-d-dire,  tres-ridneux, 
qiid  trois  ou  cinq. 

There  is  however  a  distmct  work  on  games,  entitled  Biction- 
naire  des  Jeuoc,  faisant  suite  au  Tome  III.  des  Mathematiques. 
1792.  The  Avertissement  begins  thus  :  Comme  il  y  a,  dit  Mon- 
tesquieu, une  infinite  de  choses  sages  qui  sont  menees  d'une 
mani^re  trbs-folle,  il  y  a  aussi  des  folies  qui  sont  conduites  d'une 
maniere  tr^s-sage.  The  work  contains  316  pages  of  text  and 
16  plates.  There  are  no  mathematical  investigations,  but  in  three 
cases  the  numerical  values  of  the  chances  are  given.  One  of  these 
cases  is  the  game  of  Trente  et  quarante ;  but  the  results  given  are 
inaccurate,  as  Poisson  shewed  in  the  memoir  which  we  have  cited 
in  Art.  358.  The  other  two  cases  in  which  the  results  are  given 
are  the  games  Krahs  and  Passe-dix. 

The  copy  of  the  Encyclopedie  MHliodique  which  belongs  to  the 
Cambridge  University  Library  includes  another  work  on  games 
which  is  wanting  in  other  copies  that  I  have  examined.  This  is 
entitled  Dictionnaire  des  Jeux  Mathematiques.... Kn.  Yii.  The 
advertisement  states  that  after  the  publication  of  the  Dictionary 
of  Games  in  1792  many  of  the  subscribers  requested  that  this 
treatise  should  be  enlarged  and  made  more  complete.  The  pre- 
sent Dictionary  is  divided  into  two  parts ;  first,  the  Dictionnaire 
des  Jeux  Mathematiques,  which  occupies  212  pages  ;  secondly,  a 
Dictionnaire  de  Jeux  familiers,  which  is  unfinished,  for  it  extends 
only  from  A  to  Gi^ammairien,  occupying  80  pages. 

The  Dictionnaire  des  Jeux  Mathematiques  does  not  contain 
any  thing  new  or  important  in  the  calculation  of  chances.  The 
investigations  which  are  given  are  chiefly  taken  from  Montmort, 
in  some  cases  with  a  reference  to  him,  but  more  often  without. 
Under  the  title  Joueur  we  have  the  names  of  some  writers  on  the 
subject,  and  we  find  a  very  faint  commendation  of  Montmort  to 
whose  work  the  Dictionary  is  largely  indebted ; 

Plusieiirs  aiiteurs  se  sont  exerces  sur  I'analyse  des  jeux  ;  on  en  a  im 
traite  elementaire  de  Huygens ;  on  en  a  un  phis  profoiid  de  Moivre ; 
on  a  des  morceaiix  tres-savans  de  Bernoulli  sin-  cette  matiere.  II  y  a 
un  analyse  des  jeux  de  hasard  par  Montmaur,  qui  n'est  pas  sans  m6rite. 

The  game  oi  Draughts  obtains  16  images,  and  the  game  of  Chess 


d'anieres.  445 

73  pages.  Under  the  title  Cartes  {jeu  de)  we  have  the  problem 
which  we  noticed  in  Art.  533,  omitting  however  the  part  which 
is  false. 

Under  the  title  Wliish  ou  Wisth  we  have  8  pages,  beginning 
thus : 

Jeu  de  cartes  mi-parti  de  hasard  et  de  science.  II  a  ete  invente  par 
les  Anglais,  et  continue  depuis  long  terns  d'etre  en  vogue  dans  la 
Grand-Bretagne. 

C'est  de  tons  les  jeux  de  cartes  le  plus  judicieux  dans  ses  principes, 
le  plus  convenable  a  la  societe,  le  plus  difficile,  le  plus  interessant,  le 
plus  piquant,  et  celui  qui  est  combine  avec  le  plus  d'art. 

The  article  quotes  some  of  the  results  obtained  by  De  Moivre 
in  his  calculations  of  the  chances  of  this  game  :  it  also  refers  to 
Hoyle's  work,  which  it  says  was  translated  into  French  in  1770. 

With  respect  to  the  Dictionnaire  de  Jeux  familiers  we  need 
only  say  that  it  comprises  descriptions  of  the  most  trifling  games 
which  serve  for  the  amusement  of  children ;  it  begins  with  Taime 
mon  amant par  A,  and  it  includes  Colin-Maillard. 

827.  We  next  advert  to  a  memoir  by  DAnieres,  entitled 
Reflexions  sur  les  Jeux  de  hazard. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  volume  of  the  Kouveaux 
Memoires  de  V Acad.... Berlin  for  1784;  the  date  of  publication  is 
1786  ;  the  memoir  occupies  pages  391 — 398  of  the  volume. 

The  memoir  is  not  mathematical ;  it  alludes  to  the  fact  that 
games  of  hazard  are  prohibited  by  governments,  and  shews  that 
there  are  different  kinds  of  such  games,  namely,  those  in  which  a 
man  may  ruin  his  fortune,  and  those  which  cannot  produce  more 
than  a  trifling  loss  in  any  case. 

There  is  a  memoir  by  the  same  author,  entitled  Sur  les  Paris, 
in  the  volume  of  the  Kouveaux  Memoires  de  V Acad.... Berlin  for 
1786 ;  the  date  of  publication  is  1788 :  the  memoir  occupies 
pages  273^-278  of  the  volume. 

This  memoir  is  intended  as  a  supplement  to  the  former  by  the 
same  author,  and  is  also  quite  unconnected  with  the  mathematical 
Theory  of  Probability. 

828.  We  have  now  to  notice  a  curious  work,  entitled  On  the 


446  WARING. 

Princijdes  of  translating  Algebraic  quantities  into  probable  rela- 
tions and  annuities,  (Ssc.  By  E.  Waring,  M.B.  Lucasian  Professor 
of  Mathematics  at  Cambridge,  and  Fellow  of  the  Royal  Societies 
of  London,  Bononia  and  Gottingen,  Caynbridge,  Printed  by  J.  Arch- 
deacon, Printer  to  the  University ;  For  J.  Kicholson,  Bookseller y  in 
Cambridge.     1792. 

This  is  an  octavo  pamphlet.  Besides  the  leaf  on  which  the 
title  is  printed  there  are  59  pages  of  text,  and  then  a  page  with 
a  few  corrigenda.  The  work  is  excessively  scarce ;  for  the  use 
of  a  copy  I  am  indebted  to  the  authorities  of  Queens'  College, 
Cambridge. 

829.  The  author  and  the  printer  seem  to  have  combined  their 
efforts  in  order  to  render  the  work  as  obscure  and  repulsive  as 
possible  ;  and  they  have  attained  a  fair  measure  of  success.  The 
title  is  singularly  inaccurate ;  it  is  absurd  to  pretend  to  translate 
algebraical  quantities  into  probable  relations  or  into  annuities. 
What  Waring  means  is  that  algebraical  identities  may  be  trans- 
lated so  as  to  afford  propositions  in  the  Theory  of  Probabilities  or 
in  the  Theory  of  Annuities. 

830.  Waring  begins  with  a  Lemma.  He  proposes  to  sum  the 
series 

1  +  2^-'  r  +  3^-^  r"  +  4?-^r^  +  S^'V*  +  . . .  in  infinitum. 

The  sum  will  be 

A^-Br-\-  Cr^  +  Dr'  +  ...  +y*-^ 

ii-ry 

The  coefficients  A,  B,  C ...  are  independent  of  r ;  they  must 
be  determined  by  multiplying  up  and  equating  coefficients.     Thus 

B  =  2''-''-z, 

G  =  3*-^  -  z2'-^  +  ^  ^^~  -^^ , 

j^_,z-x     ^  ^.-1  ,  g  (^  -  1)  9.-1     z{z-l)  (g-2) 
U-^     -Z6     +        ^        Z  ^-^  . 

Proceeding  in  this  way  we  shall  find  that  in  the  numerator  of 
the  fraction  which  represents  the  sum  the  last  term  is  r""^ ;  that 


WARING.  447 

is  there  is  no  power  of  r  higher  than  this  power,  and  the  coefficient 
of  this  power  is  unity.  Waring  refers  to  another  work  by  himself 
for  the  demonstration  ;  the  student  will  see  that  it  may  be  deduced 
from  the  elementary  theorem  in  Finite  Differences  respecting  the 
value  of  A"a;*^,  when  n  is  not  less  than  m. 

Waring  does  not  apply  his  Lemma  until  he  comes  to  the 
part  of  the  work  which  relates  to  Annuities,  which  forms  his 
pages  27 — 59. 

831.  Waring  now  proceeds  to  his  propositions  in  the  Theory 
of  Probabilities ;  one  of  his  examples  will  suffice  to  indicate  his 
method. 

It  is  identically  true  that   ^  — ^^^ —  =  —  —  -^ .     Suppose  -^ 

to  represent  the  chance  of  the  happening  of  an  assigned  event  in 

N  —  a 
one  trial,  and  therefore  — :^ —  the  chance  of  its  failing :  then  the 

identity  shews  that  the  chance  of  the  happening  of  the  event  in 
the  first  trial  and  its  failing  in  the  second  trial  is  equal  to  the  dif- 
ference between  the  chance  of  the  happening  of  the  event  once 
and  the  chance  of  its  happening  twice  in  succession. 

882.  There  is  nothing  of  any  importance  in  the  work  respect- 
ing the  Theory  of  Probability  until  we  come  to  page  19.  Here 
Waring  says, 

Let  the  chances  of  the  events  A  and  B  happening  be  respectively 

and  J ;   then  the  chance  of  the  event  A  happening  r  times 


a  +  h  a  +  b 

more  than  B  in  r  trials  will  be 

in  r  -f-  2  trials  will  be 


or 


a' 


{a  +  by ' 


■l+..-^li 


in  r  +  4  trials  will  be 


or 


{a  +  by\  {a+bf 


ah  r  (r  +  3)     a%- 


{a-vby\  («  +  6/  2        (a  +  6) 

and  in  general  it  will  be 


448  WARING. 


a"-      f  ah  r  (r  +  3)      a%'         r  (r  +  4)  (r  +  5)      a'6' 

{a  +  by  i  {^tT+Vf  "^        2        {a  +  by  ^ "~         [3  (^^« 

+ H — ^ ^^-^ n / TT^  + m  infinitum  >• 

\l_  (a  +  by''  j 

This  may  be  deduced  from  the  subsequent  arithmetical  theorem,  viz. 
2m{2m-l)  (2m -2)... (2m -s)         (2m-  2)(2m ~  S)...(2m -  s  -  1) 


— -  f.  ,  

+  1  [s 


r  (r  +  3)  (2m  -  4)  (2y?i  -  5) . . .  (27;t  -  g  -  2) 


1 

^(^+4)(r  +  5)   (2m-6)...(2m-s-3) 


+ 's-2 


+  ... 

+ 


T  (r  +  s  +  2)  (r  +  s  +  3) . . .  (r  +  25  +  1) 


+  1 


(r  +  27??.)  (r  +  2y?z,  -  1)  ...  (r  +  2y?i  -  s) 


s+1 


Waring's  words,  "^  happening  r  times  more  than  B"  are 
scarcely  adequate  to  convey  his  meaning.  We  see  from  the  for- 
mula he  gives  that  he  really  means  to  take  the  problem  of  the 
Duration  of  Play  in  the  case  where  B  has  a  capital  r  and  A  has  un- 
limited capital.     See  Art.  309. 

Waring  gives  no  hint  as  to  the  demonstration  of  his  arith- 
metical theorem.  We  may  demonstrate  it  thus  :  take  the  formula 
in  Art.  584,  suppose  a  =  l+^,  ^  =  1,  ^  =  ^;  we  shall  find  that 

Thus  we  get 

^-  (i+zy'^'  {1  +  zy'''^    2     (i+^r 

^  (^  +  4)  (^  +  5)         z 


U3  (1  +  z) 


t+G 


+  [4  {1  +  zy^''^"" 

Multiply  both  sides  by  (1  +  z^"^' :  thus 


WARING.  449 

(1  +  ^)'""^  =   (1   +  ZY'  +  ^^   (1   +  ^)"^"-'+  i^t^  ^2  (1   +  ^)2n-4 

If  we  exjDand  the  various  230wers  oil+  z  and  equate  the  coeffi- 
cients of  z'  we  shall  obtain  the  arithmetical  theorem  with  t  in 
place  of  r. 

But  it  is  not  obvious  how  Waring  intended  to  deduce  the 
theorem  on  the  Duration  of  Play  from  this  arithmetical  theorem.    If 

we  put  -  for  z  we  obtain 
^      a 

{a  +  hf'^'  =  a'{a  +  hf'  +  ta'  {a  +  by''-'  ah  +  H^A  a'  (a  +  1)'"-*  a'l/ 
+  ^  (^  +  ^)  (^  +  ^)  a}  (a  +  Z.)^"-^  a^Z.^  +  . . . 

and  it  was  perhaps  from  this  result  that  Waring  considered  that 
the  theorem  on  the  Duration  of  Play  might  be  deduced ;  but  it 
seems  difficult  to  render  the  process  rigidly  strict. 

833.  Waring  gives  another  problem  on  the  Duration  of  Play ; 
see  his  page  20. 

If  it  be  required  to  find  the  chance  of  ^'s  succeeding  n  times  as 
oft  as  ^'s  precisely  :  in  ?i  +  1  trials  it  will  be  found 

in  2n  +  2  trials  it  will  be  found 


P^n{n  +  \)^^^^,r.Q; 


in  3/1  +  3  it  will  be 


^     n  {n  +  1)  (?>n  +  1)       a'"6' 

V    ■• ^ ■/..     .     Z,\3n  +  3   • 


2  {a  +  by 

Waring  does  not  give  the  investigation ;  as  usual  with  him 
until  we  make  the  investigation  we  do  not  feel  quite  certain  of 
the  meaning  of  his  problem. 

The  first  of  his  three  examples  is  obvious. 

29 


450  WARING. 

In  the  second  example  we  observe  that  the  event  may  occur  m 
the  first  %  +  1  trials,  and  the  chance  of  this  is  P ;  or  the  event  may 
have  failed  in  the  first  n  +  1  trials  and  yet  may  occur  if  we  proceed 
to  «  +  1  more  trials.  This  second  case  may  occur  in  the  following 
ways :  B  may  hajDpen  twice  in  the  first  n+1  trials,  or  twice  in 
the  second  w  +  1  trials ;  while  A  happens  in  the  remaining  2)i 
trials.     Thus  we  obtain 

2  {n  +  1)  n       ^'V 


2n+2  ) 


2  [a^hf 

which  must  be  added  to  P  to  give  the  chance  in  the  second  ex- 
ami^le. 

In  the  third  example  we  observe  that  the  event  may  occur  in 
the  first  2n  +  2  trials,  and  the  chance  of  this  is  Q ;  or  the  event 
may  have  failed  in  the  first  2n-\-2  trials,  and  yet  may  occur  if  we 
proceed  to  w  +  1  more  trials.  This  second  case  may  occur  in  the 
following  ways  : 

Jj  may  happen  three  times  in  the  fii^st  n  +  1  trials,  or  three 
times  in  the  second  n+1  trials,  or  three  times  in  the  last  n  +  1 
trials ;  while  A  happens  in  the  remaining  S?i  trials. 

Or  B  may  happen  twice  in  the  first  n  +  1  trials  and  once  in  the 
second  n  +  1  trials,  or  once  in  the  second  n  +  1  trials  and  twice  in 
the  third  n  +  1  trials  ;  while  A  happens  in  the  remaining  3/^  trials. 

Thus  we  obtain 

:^  {n  +  l)nin-l)  ^  ^  {n  +  1)' nl       a'^'P 


371+3  ) 


[3  2        )  {a  +  by 

wliich  must  be  added  to  Q  to  give  the  chance  in  the  third  ex- 
ample. 

834.  *   The  following  specimen  may  be  given  of  Waring's  imper- 
fect enunciations ;  see  his  page  21  : 

Let  a,  h,  c,  d,  &c.  be  the  respective  chances  of  the  happening  of 
a,  /5,  y,  8,  &c. :  in  one  trial,  and 

(ax'^  +  hx^  +  cxy  +  doc^  +  &c.)"  =  a^x'"^  +  . . .  +  Nx^^  +  &c.; 

then  will  iV  be  the  chance  of  the  happening  of  tt  in  ti  trials. 

Nothing  is  said  as  to  what  ir  means.     The  student  will  see  that 
the  only  meaning  which  can  be  given  to  the  enunciation  is  to 


WARixa  451 

suppose  that  a,  h,  c,  d,  ...  are  the  chances  that  the  numbers 
®>  A  7j  ^>  •  •  •  respectively  will  occur  in  one  trial ;  and  then  N  is  the 
chance  that  in  n  trials  the  sum  of  the  numbers  will  be  tt. 

835.  "Waring  gives  on  his  page  22  the  theorem  which  we 
now  sometimes  call  by  the  name  of  Yanclermonde.  The  theorem 
is  that 

(a  +  Z>)  (a  +  Z»-l)  ...  (a  +  Z'-w+  1) 
=  a  (a  —  1)  .,.  [a  —  n+l) 
-f  wa  (a  —  1) . ..  (a  —  n  4-  2)  J 

+ 

+  ^^(^-1)...  {l-n+l). 

From  this  he  deduces  a  corollary  which  we  will  give  in  our 
own  notation.  Let  <f>  {x,  y)  denote  the  sum  of  the  products  that 
can  be  made  from  the  numbers  1.  2,  3,  ...  x,  taken  y  together. 
Then  will 

Li 


S  —  1 


-  (f)  ill  —  1,  ?l  —  5) 


=  ; — •  <h  (n  —  r  —  \,  n  —  s) 

I  r    \n  —  r  ^  ^ 

+      ^,    ^ -<l>{n-r-%n-s-\)<i>[r,l) 

r+1     n  —  r  —  L 


+       ..,^- ^^(n-r-3,?i-5-2)0(r+l,  2) 


r  +  2  [ 


-r-2 


n  —  r 


+  — TTTT^ ^i>{n-r-i,n-s-9)4>{r+%'i) 


+ 

It  must  be  observed  that  5  is  to  be  less  than  n,  and  r  less  than 
s ;  and  the  terms  on  the  right-hand  side  are  to  continue  until  we 
arrive  at  a  term  of  the  form  ^  {x,  0),  and  this  must  be  replaced 
by  unity. 

29—2 


452  Waring. 

This  result  is  obtained  by  equating  the  coefficients  of  the  term 
^s-rj^r  -^^  ^-j^g  ^^Q  members  of  Vandermonde's  identity. 

The  result  is  enunciated  and  printed  so  badly  in  Warings 
work  that  some  difficulty  arose  in  settling  what  the  result  was  and 
how  it  had  been  obtained. 

836.  I  do  not  enter  on  that  part  of  Waring's  work  which  relates 
to  annuities.  I  am  informed  by  Professor  De  Morgan  that  the  late 
Francis  Baily  mentions  in  a  letter  the  following  as  the  interesting 

parts  of  the  work  : — the  series  8  —  mS'  -\ ^-^ S"  —  ....,    the 

Problem  III,   and  the  observations  on  assurances  payable  imme- 
diately at  death. 

837.  Another  work  by  Waring  requires  a  short  notice ;  it  is 
entitled  A^i  essay  on  the  jirinciples  of  human  knowledge.  Cam- 
bridge  1794.  This  is  an  octavo  volume  ;  it  contains  the  title-leaf, 
then  240  pages,  then  3  pages  of  Addenda,  and  a  page  containing 
Corrige7ida. 

838.  This  work  contains  on  pages  35 — 40  a  few  common  theo- 
rems of  probability ;  the  first  two  pages  of  the  Addenda  briefly 
notice  the  problem  discussed  by  De  Moivre  and  others  about  a 
series  of  letters  being  in  their  proper  places  ;  see  Art.  281,  and  De 
Moivre  Prob.  xxxv.  Waring  remarks  that  if  the  number  of 
letters  is  infinite  the  chance  that  they  will  occur  all  in  their  right 
places  is  infinitesimal.  He  gives  page  49  of  his  work  as  that  on 
which  this  remark  bears,  but  it  would  seem  that  49  is  a  misprint 
for  41. 

839.  Two  extracts  may  be  given  from  this  book. 

I  know  that  some  mathematicians  of  the  first  class  have  endeavoured 
to  demonstrate  the  degree  of  probabihty  of  an  event's  happening  7^  times 
from  its  having  happened  m  preceding  times;  and  consequently  that 
such  an  event  will  probably  take  place ;  but,  alas,  the  problem  far  ex- 
ceeds the  extent  of  human  understanding :  who  can  determine  the  time 
when  the  sun  will  probably  cease  to  run  its  present  course  ?     Page  35. 

...I  have  myself  wrote  on  most  subjects  in  pure  matliematics,  and  in 


ANCILLON.  453 

these  books  inserted  nearly  all  tlie   inventions   of  the  moderns  with 
which  I  was  acquainted. 

In  my  prefaces  I  have  given  an  history  of  the  inventions  of  the  dif- 
ferent writers,  and  ascribed  them  to  their  respective  authors  ;  and  like- 
wise some  account  of  my  own.  To  every  one  of  these  sciences  I  have 
been  able  to  make  some  additions,  and  in  the  whole,  if  I  am  not  mis- 
taken in  enumerating  them,  somewhere  between  three  and  four  hundred 
new  propositions  of  one  kind  or  other,  considerably  more  than  have 
been  given  by  any  English  writer ;  and  in  novelty  and  diiEculty  not 
inferior ;  I  wish  I  could  subjoin  in  utility  :  many  more  might  have 
been  added,  but  I  never  could  hear  of  any  reader  in  England  out  of 
Cambridge,  who  took  the  pains  to  read  and  understand  what  I  have 
written.     Page  115. 

Waring  proceeds  to  console  himself  under  this  neglect  in  Eng- 
land by  the  honour  conferred  on  him  by  D'Alembert,  Euler  and 
Le  Grange. 

Dugald  Stewart  makes  a  remark  relating  to  Waring;  see  his 
Works  edited  hy  Hamilton,  Vol.  IV,  page  218. 

840.  A  memoir  by  Ancillon,  entitled  Doutes  sur  les  bases  du 
calcul  des  probabiliUs,  was  pviblished  in  the  volume  for  1794  and 
1795  of  the  Memoires  de  F Acad.... Berlin;  the  memoir  occupies 
pages  3 — 32  of  the  part  of  the  volume  which  is  devoted  to  specu- 
lative philosophy. 

The  memoir  contains  no  mathematical  investigations ;  its  ob- 
ject is  to  throw  doubts  on  the  possibility  of  constructing  a  Theory 
of  Probability,  and  it  is  of  very  little  value.  The  author  seems  to 
have  determined  that  no  Theory  of  Probability  coidd  be  con- 
structed without  giving  any  attention  to  the  Theory  which  had 
been  constructed.  He  names  Moses  Mendelsohn  and  Garve  as 
having  already  examined  the  question  of  the  admissibility  of  such 
a  Theory. 

841.  There  are  three  memoirs  wTitten  by  Pre  vest  and  Lhuilier 
in  conjunction  and  published  in  the  volume  for  1796  of  the 
Memoires  de  VAcad... .Berlin.     The  date  of  pubhcation  is  1799. 

842.  The  first  memoir  is  entitled  Sur  les  Prohahilites ;  it  was 
read  Nov.  12,  1795.  It  occupies  pages  117— 14^2  of  the  mathe- 
matical portion  of  the  volume. 


4oJ<  PREVOST   AND   LHUILIER. 

843.  The  memoir  is  devoted  to  the  following  problem.  An 
urn  contains  m  balls  some  of  which  are  white  and  the  rest  black, 
but  the  number  of  each  is  unknown.  Suppose  that  p  white  balls 
and  q  black  balls  have  been  drawn  and  not  replaced ;  required  the 
probability  that  out  of  the  next  r  +  s  drawings  r  shall  give  white 
balls  and  s  black  balls. 

The  possible  hypotheses  as  to  the  original  state  of  the  urn  are, 
that  there  were  q  black  balls,  or  g  + 1  black  balls,  or  q-\-2,  ... 
or  m  —  p.  Now  form  the  probability  of  these  various  hypotheses 
according  to  the  usual  principles.     Let 

P^—  (qn  —  q  —  n -^V)  {m  —  q  —  n) to  p  factors, 

§„=  (g'  4-  ^  —  1)  C*/  +  w  —  2) to  q  factors  ; 

then  the  probability  of  the  /i*'^  hypothesis  is 

P  0 

where  S  denotes  the  sum  of  all  such  products  as  P„^„.  Now  if 
this  hypothesis  were  certainly  true  the  chance  of  drawing  r  white 
balls  and  s  black  balls  in  the  next  r-\-s  drawings  would  be 


'^n'^n 


where 

Bn=  {m  —  q  —  p  —  n  +  1)  {m  —  q—p  —  n) to  r  factors, 

^n  =  (^  —  1)  («  —  2) to  5  factors, 

iV=  number  of  combinations  oi  m—p—  q  things  r  +  5  at  a  time. 

Thus  the  whole  required  probability  is  the  sum  of  all  the 
terms  of  which  the  type  is 

We  have  first  to  find  2.  The  method  of  induction  is  adopted 
in  the  original  memoir ;  we  may  however  readily  obtain  X  by  the 
aid  of  the  binomial  theorem :  see  Algebra,  Chapter  L.  Thus  we 
shall  find 

[p_\q_  [m  +  1 


[p  +  q  +  1    \m  —  p  —  q 


PREVOST   AND    LHUILIER.  455 

Now  PnJ^n  differs  from  P^  only  in  having  p  +  r  instead  of  p  ; 
and  QnS,^  difiers  from  Q^  only  in  having  q-\-s  instead  of  q^.  There- 
fore the  sum  of  all  the  terms  of  the  form  P„  QnP^n^n  is 

\p  +  r\q  +  s  I  ??i  +  1 


p-{-q  +  r-\-s-\-l   \ni  —  p  —  q  —  r  —  s 


in  —  p  —  q 
And  .Y=  '  ^ 


r  -\-  s    m  —  p  —  q  —  r  —  s 


Thus  finally  the  required  probability  is 

\r  -\-  s  '  p  +  r  \  q  -{■  s  \p  -\-  q  +  1 


\IL\1  [rVL  \l)-\-q-\-r  +  s-\-l  ' 


844.  Let  us  supf)Ose  that  r  and  5  vary  while  their  sum  r  +  5 
remains  constant ;  then  we  can  a^^ply  the  preceding  general 
result  to  ?'  +  5  +  l  different  cases;  namely  the  case  in  which  all 
the  r  +  s  drawings  are  to  give  white  balls,  or  all  but  one,  or  all  but 
two,  and  so  on,  down  to  the  case  in  which  none  are  white.  The 
sum  of  these  probabilities  ought  to  he  unitif,  which  is  a  test  of  the 
accuracy  of  the  result.  This  verification  is  given  in  the  original 
memoir,  by  the  aid  of  a  theorem  which  is  proved  by  induction. 
No  new  theorem  however  is  required,  for  we  have  only  to  apply 
again  the  formula  by  which  we  found  S  in  the  preceding  Ai'ticle. 
The  variable  2')art  of  the  result  of  the  preceding  Article  is 

}:)-{-  r  \q  +  s 


that  is  the  product  of  the  following  two  expressions, 

(r  +  1)  (r  4-  2) p)  factors, 

(5  +  1)  (5  +  2) q  factors. 

The  sum  of  such  products  then  is  to  be  found  supposing  r  +  5 
constant ;  and  this  is 


p-\-q  +  l  r  + 


Hence  the  required  result,  unity,  is  obtained  by  multiplying 
this  expression  by  the  constant  part  of  the  result  in  the  preceding- 
Article. 


45 G  PEEVOST   AND    LHUILIER. 

This  result  had  been  noticed  by  Condorcet ;  see  page  189  of 
the  Essai...  de  l' Analyse... 

845.  Out  of  the  r  +  s  +  1  cases  considered  in  the  preceding 
Article,  suppose  we  ask  which  has  the  greatest  probability  ?  This 
question  is  answered  in  the  memoir  approximately  thus.  A  quan- 
tity when  approaching  its  maximum  value  varies  slowly  ;  thus  we 
have  to  find  when  the  result  at  the  end  of  Article  843  remains 
nearly  unchanged  if  we  put  r  —  1  for  r  and  s  + 1  for  s.  This 
leads  to 

p  +  r      (7  +  5  +  1  , 
= z. —  ,  nearly  ; 

therefore  -  =  — ~-  nearly. 

r      s  ■\-l  ^ 

T        7) 

Thus  if  r  and  s  are  laro^e  we  have  -  =  -  nearly. 

s     <i  ^ 

846.  It  will  be  observed  that  the  expression  at  the  end  of 
Art.  843  is  independent  of  m  the  number  of  balls  originally  con- 
tained in  the  urn ;  the  memoir  notices  this  and  draws  attention 
to  the  fact  that  this  is  not  the  case  if  each  ball  is  replaced  in  the 
urn  after  it  has  been  drawn.  It  is  stated  that  another  memoir 
will  be  given,  which  will  consider  this  form  of  the  problem  when 
the  number  of  balls  is  supposed  infinite ;  but  it  does  not  seem  that 
this  intention  was  carried  into  effect. 

847.  It  will  be  instructive  to  make  the  comparison  between 
the  two  problems  which  we  may  pi'esume  would  have  formed  the 
substance  of  the  projected  memoir.  Suppose  that  j:>  white  balls 
have  been  drawn  and  q  black  balls,  and  not  replaced;  and  suppose 
the  whole  number  of  balls  to  be  infinite  :  then  by  Art.  704  the  pro- 
bability that  the  next  r  +  s  drawings  will  give  r  white  balls  and  s 
black  balls  is 


and  on  effectinf]^  the  intecjration  we  obtain  the  same  result  as  in 


PREVOST    AND    LHUILIER.  457 

Art.  843.    The  coincidence  of  the  results  obtained  on  the  two  dif- 
ferent hypotheses  is  remarkable. 

848.  Suppose  that  r  =  1  and  5  =  0  in  the  result  of  Art.  843  ; 
we  thus  obtain 

p-hl 

Again  suppose  ?^  =  2  and  5  =  0;  we  thus  obtain 

The  factor  -^ is,  as  we  have  just  seen,  the  probability 

of  drawing  another  white  ball  after  drawing  p  white  balls  and 

p  +  2 

q  black  balls  ;  the  factor  — expresses  in  like  manner  the 

^  7^  +  ^  +  3       ^ 

probability  of  drawing  another  white  ball  after  drawing^ +  1  white 

balls  and  q  black  balls  :  thus  the  formula  makes  the  probability 

of  drawing  two  white  balls  in  succession  equal  to  the  product  of 

the  probability  of  drawing  the  first  into  the  probability  of  drawing 

the  second,  as  should  be  the  case.     This  property  of  the  formula 

holds  generally. 

849.  The  memoir  which  we  have  now  examined  contains  the 
first  discussion  of  the  problem  to  which  it  relates,  namely,  the 
problem  in  which  the  balls  are  not  replaced.  A  particular  case  of 
the  problem  is  considered  by  Bishop  Terrot  in  the  Transactions  of 
the  Royal  Society  of  Edinburgh,  Vol.  xx. 

850.  The  other  two  memoirs  to  which  we  have  referred  in 
Art.  841  are  less  distinctly  mathematical,  and  they  are  accordingly 
printed  in  the  portion  of  the  volume  which  is  devoted  to  speculative 
philosophy.  The  second  memoir  occupies  pages  3 — 24,  and  the 
third  memoir  pages  25 — 41.  A  note  relating  to  a  passage  of  the 
third  memoir,  by  the  authors  of  the  memoir,  is  given  in  the  volume 
for  1797  of  the  Memoires  de  V Acad.... Berlin,  page  152. 

851.  The  second  memoir  is  entitled  8ur  Vart  d'estimer  la 
prohabilite  des  causes  par  les  effets.  It  consists  of  two  sections. 
The  first  section  discusses  the   general   principle  by  which  the 


458  PREVOST  AND   LHUILIER. 

probabilities  of  causes  are  estimated.  The  principle  is  quoted  as 
given  by  Laplace  in  the  Memoires . .  .par  divers  Savans,  Yol.  VI. : 
Si  un  evenement  pent  etre  produit  par  un  nombre  n  de  causes 
differentes,  les  probabilites  de  I'existence  de  ces  causes  prises  de 
I'evdnement,  sont  entre  elles  comme  les  probabilites  de  I'evene- 
ment  prises  de  ces  causes.  The  memoir  considers  it  useful  and 
necessary  to  demonstrate  this  principle ;  and  accordingly  deduces 
it  from  a  simple  hypothesis  on  which  it  is  conceived  that  the  whole 
subject  rests.  Some  remarks  made  by  Condorcet  are  criticised ; 
and  it  is  asserted  that  our  persuasion  of  the  constancy  of  the  laws 
of  nature  is  not  of  the  same  kind  as  that  which  is  represented  by 
a  fraction  in  the  Theory  of  Probability.  See  Dugald  Stewart's 
Works  edited  hy  Hamilton,  Yol.  i.  pages  421,  616. 

The  second  section  of  the  memoir  applies  Laplace's  principle 
to  some  easy  examples  of  the  following  kind.  A  die  has  a  certain 
number  of  faces ;  the  markings  on  these  faces  are  not  known,  but 
it  is  observed  that  out  of  ^  +  ^  throws  p  have  given  ace  and  q 
not-ace.  Find  the  probability  that  there  is  a  certain  number  of 
faces  marked  ace.  Also  find  the  probability  that  in  p'  +  q'  more 
throws  there  will  bej/  aces  and  q  not-aces. 

It  is  shewn  that  the  result  in  the  last  case  is 

where  2  denotes  a  summation  taken  with  respect  to  m  from  m  =  1 

to  m  =  n',  and  7i  is  the  whole  number  of  faces.     This  is  the  result 

if  the  aces  and  not-aces  are  to  come  in  a  prescribed  order  \  if  they 

I  //  +  q 
are  not  we  must  multiply  by  — ;- — r- . 

^  *^     *^       p    \q 


The  memoir  states  without  demonstration  what  the  approxi- 
mate result  is  when  n  is  supposed  very  great ;  namely,  for  the 
case  in  which  the  order  is  prescribed. 


Li  L^       \p  +  q+p  +  </'  +  !' 


852.     The  third  memoir  is  entitled  Remarques  siir  Vutilite  et 
Vetendue  dii  2)7'inci2)e  par  lequel  on  estime  la  p^i'ohahilite  des  causes. 
This  memoir  also  relates  to  the  principle  which  we  have  quoted 


PREVOST   AND    LHUILIER.  459 

in   Art.  851    from   Laplace.     The   memoir   is   divided   into   four 
sections. 

853.  The  first  section  is  on  the  lUility  of  the  principle.  It  is 
asserted  that  before  the  epoch  when  this  principle  was  laid  down 
many  errors  had  occurred  in  the  waiters  on  Probability. 

The  following  paragraph  is  given  : 

Dans  I'appreciation  de  la  valeur  dii  temoignage  de  deux  tenioias 
simultanes,  il  paroit  que,  jusqu'a  Lambert,  on  n'a  point  use  d'un  autre 
artifice,  que  de  prendre  le  comjDlement  de  la  formule  employee  pour  le 
temoignage  successif.  On  suivoit  ^  cet  egard  la  trace  de  I'appreciation 
des  argumens  conspirans,  telle  que  I'avoit  faite  Jac.  Bernoulli.  Si  I'on 
avoit  connu  la  vraie  methode  de  I'estimation  des  causes,  on  n'auroit  pas 
manque  d' examiner  avant  tout  si  ce  cas  s'y  rapportoit ;  et  Ton  auroit  vu 
que  I'accord  entre  les  temoins  est  un  evenement  posterieur  k  la  cause 
quelconque  qui  a  determine  les  depositions  :  en  sorte  qu'il  s'agit  ici 
d'estimer  la  cause  par  I'efiet.  On  seroit  ainsi  retorabe  tout  naturelle- 
ment  et  sans  effort  dans  la  methode  que  Lambert  a  trouvee  par  un 
effet  de  cette  sagacite  rare  qui  caracterisoit  son  genie. 

854.  The  authors  of  the  memoir  illustrate  this  section  by 
quoting  from  a  French  translation,  published  in  Paris  in  1786,  of 
a  w^ork  by  Haygarth  on  the  small-pox.  Haygarth  obtained  from  a 
mathematical  friend  the  following  remark.  Assuming  that  out 
of  tAventy  persons  exjDosed  to  the  contagion  of  the  small-jDox 
only  one  escapes,  then,  however  violent  the  small-pox  mav 
be  in  a  town  if  an  infant  has  not  taken  the  disease  we  may 
infer  that  it  is  19  to  1  that  he  has  not  been  exposed  to  the 
contagion ;  if  two  in  a  family  have  escaped  the  probability  that 
both  have  not  been  exposed  to  the  contagion  is  more  than  400  to  1 ; 
if  three  it  is  more  than  8000  to  1. 

With  respect  to  this  statement  the  memoir  says  that  M.  de  la 
Roche  the  French  translator  has  shewn  that  it  is  ^ATong  by  a  judi- 
cious discussion.  The  end  of  the  translator's  note  is  quoted  ;  the 
chief  part  of  this  quotation  is  the  following  sentence  : 

Si  Ton  a  observe  que  sur  vingt  persounes  qui  pontent  a  une  table  de 
pharaon  il  y  en  a  dix-neuf  qui  se  ruinent,  on  ne  pourra  pas  en  deduire 
qu'il  y  a  un  a  parier  centre  dix-neuf  que  tout  homme  dont  la  foi-tune 


4  GO  HAYGAETH. 

n  est  pas  derangee,  n'a  pas  ponte  au  pliaraon,  ni  qu'il  y  ait  dix-neuf  a 
parier  centre  un,  que  cet  liomme  est  un  joueur. 

This  would  be  absurd,  M.  de  la  Roche  says,  and  he  asserts  that 
the  reasoning  given  by  Haygarth's  friend  is  equally  absurd.  We 
may  remark  that  there  must  be  some  mistake  in  this  note  ;  he  has 
put  19  to  1  for  1  to  19,  and  vice  versa.  And  it  is  difficult  to  see  how 
Prevost  and  Lhuilier  can  commend  this  note ;  for  M.  de  la  Roche 
argues  that  the  reasoning  of  Haygarth's  friend  is  entirely  absurd, 
while  they  only  find  it  slightly  inaccurate.  For  Prevost  and 
Lhuilier  proceed  to  calculate  the  chances  according  to  Laplace's 

prmciple ;  and  they  nnd  them  to  be  ^ ,    — — - ,    — — -  ,  which,  as 

they  say,  are  nearly  the  same  as  the  results  obtained  by  Hay- 
garth's friend. 

855.  The  second  section  is  on  the  extent  of  the  principle.  The 
memoir  asserts  that  we  have  a  conviction  of  the  constancy  of  the 
laws  of  nature,  and  that  we  rely  on  this  constancy  in  our  applica- 
tion of  the  Theory  of  Probability ;  and  thus  we  reason  in  a  vicious 
circle  if  we  pretend  to  apply  the  principle  to  questions  respecting 
the  constancy  of  such  laws. 

856.  The  third  section  is  devoted  to  the  comparison  of  some 
results  of  the  Theory  of  Probability  with  common  sense  notions. 

In  the  formula  at  the  end  of  Art.  843  suppose  5  =  0;  the  for- 
mula reduces  to 

{p+  1)  (jP  +  2)  ...  (p  +  r) 

(p+2+2)  (;?  +  $  + 3)  ...  (^  +  g  +  r  +  l)  ' 

it  is  this  result  of  which  particular  cases  are  considered  in  the 
third  section.  The  cases  are  such  as  according  to  the  memoir  lead 
to  conclusions  coincident  with  the  notions  of  common  sense ;  in 
one  case  however  this  is  not  immediately  obvious,  and  the  memoir 
says,  Ceci  donne  I'explication  d'une  esp(^ce  de  paradoxe  remarque 
(sans  I'expliquer)  par  M.  De  La  Place  ;  and  a  reference  is  given  to 
Ecoles  no7miaIes,  Qimie  cahier.  We  will  give  this  case.  Nothing  is 
known  d,  priori  respecting  a  certain  die  ;  it  is  observed  on  trial  that 
in  five  throws  ace  occurs  twice  and  not-ace  three  times ;  find  the 
probability  that   the  next  four  throws  will  all  give   ace.     Here 


PREYOST   AND   LHUILIER.  461 

3,4.5.6  1 

p=  2,  q=S,  r  =4  ;  the  above  result  becomes  ^  o^~n  a  >  that  is  — . 

If  we  knew  a  priori  that  the  die  had  as  many  faces  ace  as  not-ace 
we  should  have  -^^ ,  that  is  ^5  '  ^^^'  ^^^^  required  chance.    The  para- 

dox  is  that  q-  is  o-reater  than  — ; ;  while  the  fact  that  we  have  had 
14  lb 

only  two  aces  out  of  five  throws  suggests  that  we  ought  to  have  a 

smaller  chance  for  obtaining  four  consecutive  aces,  than  we  should 

have  if  we  knew  that  the  die  had  the  same  number  of  faces  ace  as 

not-ace.     We  need  not  give  the  explanation  of  the  paradox,  as  it 

will  be  found  in  connexion  with  a  similar  example  in  Laplace, 

Theorie...des  Proh.  page  cvi. 

857.  The  fourth  section  gives  some  mathematical  develop- 
ments. The  following  is  the  substance.  Suppose  n  dice,  each 
having  r  faces  ;  and  let  the  number  of  faces  which  are  marked  ace 
be  m,  m\  m"\  . . .  respectively.  If  a  die  is  taken  at  random,  the 
probability  of  throwing  ace  is 

on  -\-m   -^-m    +  ... 


nr 
If  an  ace  has  been  thrown  the  probability  of  throwing  ace  again 
on  a  second  trial  with  the  same  die  is 

m^  +  m"  +  m""  +  . . . 


r  [in  -{■  m   -\- m    +  ...) 
The  first  probability  is  the  greater;  for 

{m  +  m  4- m"  +  ...y  is  greater  than  n  [m^  +  m'"^  +  m"'^  +  ...). 
The  memoir  demonstrates  this  simple  inequality. 

858.  Prevost  and  Lhuilier  are  also  the  authors  of  a  memoir 
entitled  Me  mo  ire  sur  ^application  du  Calcid  des  prohahilites  a  la 
valeur  du  temoignage. 

This  memoir  is  published  in  the  volume  for  1797  of  the  Me- 
moires  de  V Acad.... Berlin;  the  date  of  publication  is  1800:  the 
memoir  occupies  pages  120 — 151  of  the  portion  of  the  volume 
devoted  to  speculative  philosophy. 

The  memoir  begins  thus  : 

Le  but  de  ce  memoire  est  plutot  de  reconnoitre  I'etat  actuel  de  cette 
theorie,  que  d'y  rien  aj  outer  de  nouveau. 


462  PREVOST  AND   LHUILIER. 

The  memoir  first  notices  tlie  criticism  given  in  Lambert's  Orga- 
non  of  James  Bernoulli's  formula  winch  we  have  already  given  in 
Art.  122. 

It  then  passes  on  to  the  theory  of  concurrent  testimony  now 
commonly  received.  Suppose  a  witness  to  speak  truth  m  times  and 
falsehood  n  times  out  oi  m  +  n  times ;  let  m  and  ?i'  have  similar 
meanings  for  a  second  witness.     Then  if  they  agree  in  an  assertion 

the  probability  of  its  truth  is -, r  • 

mm  ■\-n7i 

The  ordinary  theory  of  traditional  testimony  is  also  given. 
Using  the  same  notation  as  before  if  one  witness  reports  a  state- 
ment from  the  report  of  another  the  probability  of  its  truth  is 

mm'  +  nn 


J\    5 


{m  +  m')  {71  +  n) 

for  the  statement  is  true  if  they  both  tell  the  truth  or  if  they  both 
tell  a  falsehood.  If  there  be  two  witnesses  in  succession  each  of 
whom  reverses  the  statement  he  ought  to  give,  the  result  is  true  ; 
that  is  a  double  falsehood  gives  a  truth.  It  is  stated  that  this  con- 
sequence was  first  indicated  in  1794  by  Prevost. 

The  hypothesis  of  Craig  is  noticed  ;  see  Art.  91. 

The  only  new  point  in  the  memoir  is  an  hypothesis  which  is 
proposed  relating  to  traditional  testimony,  and  which  is  admitted 
to  be  arbitrary,  but  of  which  the  consequences  are  examined.  The 
hypothesis  is  that  no  testimony  founded  on  falsehood  can  give  the 
truth.    The  meaning  of  this  hypothesis  is  best  seen  by  an  example: 

suppose  the  two  witnesses  precisely  alike,  then  instead  of  taking 

2  I     2 
071  "t"  n 

-7 rr  as  the  probability  of  the  truth  in  the  case  above  considered 

{m  -\-n) 


m^ 


we  should  take rj  :   that  is  we  reject  the  term  n^  in  the 

[m  +  n)  ** 

numerator  which  arises  from  the  agreement  of  the  witnesses  in  a 

falsehood. 

rrn  J  1  ^^  1  ^nm  -\-n^  ,  ,  .     , 

Ihus  we  take  7 V2  ^'^^  -, \¥  to  represent  respectively 

[in  +  n)  {in  +  ^)  ^  ^  -^ 

the  probabilities  of  the  truth  and  falsehood  of  the  statement  on 
which  the  witnesses  agree. 

Suppose  now  that  there  is  a  second  pair  of  witnesses  inde- 
pendent of  the  former,  of  the  same  character,  and  that  the  same 


MATTHEW   YOUNG.  463 

statement  is  also  affirmed  by  this  pair.  Then  the  memoir  combines 
the  two  pairs  by  the  ordinary  rule  for  concurrent  testimony,  and  so 
takes  for  the  probability  arising  from  the  two  pairs 


m^  -f  i^nm  +  iff  ' 
Then  the  question  is  asked  for  what  ratio  of  m  to  n  this  expres- 

sion  is  equal  to ,  so  that  the  force  of  the  two  pairs  of  wit- 

m  -^  n  ^ 

nesses  may  be  equal  to  that  of  a  single  witness.     The  approximate 

value  of  —  is  said  to  be  4*86^  so  that is  about  -^  . 

n  m-\-  n  b 

859.  In  Vol.  VII.  of  the  Transactions  of  the  Royal  Irish 
Academy  there  is  a  memoir  by  the  Rev.  Matthew  Young,  D.D. 
S.F.T.c.D.  and  M.R.I.A.,  entitled  On  the  force  of  Testimony  in  esta- 
hlishing  Facts  contrai^y  to  Analogy.  The  date  of  publication  of 
the  volume  is  1800 ;  the  memoir  was  read  February  3rd,  1798  :  it 
occupies  pages  79 — 118  of  the  volume. 

The  memoir  is  rather  metaphysical  than  mathematical.  Dr 
Young  may  be  said  to  adopt  the  modern  method  of  estimating  the 
force  of  the  testimony  of  concurrent  witnesses ;  in  this  method, 
supposing  the  witnesses  of  equal  credibility,  we  obtain  a  formula 
coincidino^  with  that  in  Art.  667.  Dr  Younof  condemns  as  erroneous 
the  method  which  we  noticed  in  Art.  91 ;  he  calls  it  "Dr  Halley's 
mode,"  but  gives  no  authority  for  this  designation.  Dr  Young 
criticises  two  rules  given  by  Waring  on  the  subject ;  in  the  first  of 
the  two  cases  however  it  would  not  be  difficult  to  explain  and 
defend  Waring's  rule. 


CHAPTER   XX. 


LAPLACE. 

860.  Laplace  was  born  in  1749,  and  died  in  1827.  He  wrote 
elaborate  memoirs  on  our  subject,  which  he  afterwards  embodied 
in  his  great  work  the  Theorie  analytique  des  ProhabiliUs,  and  on 
the  whole  the  Theory  of  Probability  is  more  indebted  to  him  than 
to  any  other  mathematician.  We  shall  give  in  the  first  place  a 
brief  account  of  Laplace's  memoirs,  and  then  consider  more  fully 
the  work  in  which  they  are  reproduced. 

861.  Two  memoirs  by  Laplace  on  our  subject  are  contained  in 
the  Memoir es...pa7^  divers  Savans,  Vol.  vi.  1774.  A  brief  notice 
of  the  memoirs  is  given  in  pages  17 — 19  of  the  preface  to  the 
volume  which  concludes  thus  : 

Ces  deux  Memoires  de  M.  de  la  Place,  ont  ete  choisis  parmi  un 
tres-grand  nombre  qu'il  a  presentes  depuis  trois  ans,  a  I'Academie,  oii  il 
remplit  actuellement  une  place  de  Geometre.  Cette  Compagnie  qui  s'est 
empressee  de  recorapenser  ses  travaux  et  ses  talens,  n'avoit  encore  vu 
personne  aussi  jeune,  lui  presenter  en  si  peu  de  temps,  tant  de  Memoires 
importans,  et  sur  des  matieres  si  diverses  et  si  difficiles. 

862.  The  first  memoir  is  entitled  Memoir e  sur  les  suites  re- 
ciirro-recurrentes  et  sur  leurs  usages  dans  la  theorie  des  hasards.  It 
occupies  pages  353 — 371  of  the  volume. 

A  recurring  series  is  connected  with  the  solution  of  an  equation 
in  Finite  Differences  where  there  is  one  independent  variable ;  see 
Art.  318.  A  recurro-recurrent  series  is  similarly  connected  with 
the  solution  of  an  equation  in  Finite  Differences  where  there  are 
two  independent  variables.     Laplace  here  first  introduces  the  term 


LAPLACE.  4G5 

and  the  subject  itself;  we  shall  not  give  any  account  of  his  investi- 
gations, but  confine  ourselves  to  the  part  of  his  memoir  which 
relates  to  the  Theory  of  Probability. 

863.  Laplace  considers  three  problems  in  our  subject.  The 
first  is  the  problem  of  the  Duration  of  Play,  supposing  two  players 
of  unequal  skill  and  unequal  capital ;  Laplace,  however,  rather 
shews  how  the  j)i"oblem  may  be  solved  than  actually  solves  it.  He 
begins  with  the  case  of  equal  skill  and  equal  caj^ital,  and  then 
passes  on  to  the  case  of  unequal  skill.  He  proceeds  so  far  as  to 
obtain  an  equation  in  Finite  Differences  with  one  independent 
variable  which  would  present  no  difficulty  in  solving.  He  does 
not  actually  discuss  the  case  of  unequal  capital,  but  intimates  that 
there  will  be  no  obstacle  except  the  length  of  the  process. 

The  problem  is  solved  completely  in  the  Theorie...des  Proh. 
pages  225—238  ;  see  Art.  588. 

8GL  The  next  problem  is  that  connected  with  a  lottery  which 
appears  in  the  Theorie...des  Proh.  pages  191 — 201.  The  mode  of 
solution  is  nearly  the  same  in  the  two  places,  but  it  is  easier  to 
follow  in  the  Theorie...des  Proh.  The  memoir  does  not  contain 
any  of  the  approximate  calculation  which  forms  a  large  part  of  the 
diiicussion  in  the  Theorie,..des  Proh.  ^Ye  have  already  given  the 
history  of  the  problem;  see  Arts.  -11:8,  775. 

865.  The  third  problem  is  the  following :  Out  of  a  heap  of 
counters  a  number  is  taken  at  random ;  find  the  chances  that  this 
number  will  be  odd  or  even  respectively.  Laplace  obtains  what  we 
should  now  call  the  ordinary  results  ;  his  method  however  is  more 
elaborate  than  is  necessary,  for  he  uses  Finite  Differences  :  in  the 
Tlieorie...des  Proh.  page  201,  he  gives  a  more  simj^le  solution. 
We  have  already  sjDoken  of  the  problem  in  Art.  350. 

866.  The  next  memoir  is  entitled  Memoire  sur  la  Prohahilite 
des  causes  par  les  echiemens ;  it  occupies  pages  621 — QoQ  of  the 
volume  cited  in  Art.  861. 

The  memoir  commences  thus  : 

La  Theorie  des  hasarda  est  une  dcs  parties  les  plus  curieuses  et  les 

30 


4G6  LAPLACE. 

plus  del'cates  de  I'analyse,  par  la  finesse  dcs  comblnaisons  qu'elle  exige 
et  par  la  difficulte  de  les  soumettre  au  calcul ;  celui  qui  paroit  I'avoir 
traitee  avec  le  pins  de  succcs  estM.  Moivre,  dans  un  excellent  Oiivrage 
qui  a  pour  titre,  Theory  of  Chances ;  nous  devons  a  cet  habile  Geometre 
les  premieres  rocherches  que  Ton  ait  faites  sur  Fintegration  des  equa- 
tions differencielles  aux  differences  finies ;  ... 

867.  Laplace  then  refers  to  Lagrange's  researches  on  the 
theory  of  equations  in  Finite  Differences,  and  also  to  two  of  his 
own  memoirs,  namely  that  which  we  have  just  examined,  and  one 
wdiich  was  about  to  appear  in  the  volume  of  the  Academy  for 
1773.  But  his  present  object,  he  says,  is  very  different,  and  is 
thus  stated : 

...je  me  propose  de  determiner  la  probabilite  des  causes  par  les 
evenemens,  maticre  neuve  a  bicn  des  egards  et  qui  merite  d'autant  plus 
d'etre  cultivee  que  c'est  principalement  sous  ce  point  de  vue  que  la 
science  des  hasards  pent  etre  utile  dans  la  vie  civile. 

868.  This  memoir  is  remarkable  in  the  history  of  the  subject, 
as  being  the  first  which  distinctly  enunciated  the  principle  for 
estimating  the  probabilities  of  the  causes  by  which  an  observed 
event  may  have  been  produced.  Bayes  must  have  had  a  notion  of 
the  principle,  and  Laplace  refers  to  him  in  the  Theorie...des  Proh. 
page  cxxxvii.  though  Bayes  is  not  named  in  the  memoir.  See 
Arts.  539,  696. 

869.  Laplace  states  the  general  principle  which  he  assumes  in 
the  follow^ing  words  : 

Si  un  evenement  peut  etre  produit  par  un  nombre  n  de  causes  dif- 
ferentes,  les  probabilites  de  I'existence  de  ces  causes  prises  de  I'evene- 
ment,  sent  entre  elles  comme  les  probabilites  de  I'evenement  prises  de 
ces  causes,  et  la  probabilite  de  I'existence  de  cliacune  d'elles,  est  egale 
a  la  probabilite  de  I'evenement  prise  de  cette  cause,  divisee  par  la  somme 
de  toutes  les  probabilites  de  Tevenement  prises  de  chacune  de  ces 
causes. 

870.  Laplace  first  takes  tlie  standard  problem  in  this  part  of 
our  subject :  Suppose  that  an  urn  contains  an  infinite  number  of 
white  tickets  and  black  tickets  in  an  unknown  ratio ;  ^  +  </  tickets 


LAPLACE.  467 

are  drawn  of  which  p  are  white  and  q  are  black  :  required  the  pro- 
bability of  drawing  m  white  tickets  and  n  black  tickets  in  the  next 
m  +  n  drawings. 

Laplace  gives  for  the  required  probability 


/, 


a^^'"  (1  _  xY'-''  clx 


j  x"  (1  -xydx 

'^  0 

so  that  of  course  the  m  white  tickets  and  n  black  tickets  are  sup- 
posed to  be  draT^^l  in  an  assigned  order ;  see  Arts.  ^0^,  76G,  843. 
Laplace  effects  the  integration,  and  approximates  by  the  aid  of  a 
formula  which  he  takes  from  Euler,  and  which  we  usually  call 
Stirling's  Theorem. 

The  problem  here  considered  is  not  explicitly  reproduced  in  the 
Theorie. .  .des  Proh.,  though  it  is  involved  in  the  Chapter  which  forms 
pages  363—401. 

871.     After  discussing  this  problem  Laplace  says, 

La  solution  de  ce  Probleme  donne  une  methode  directe  pour  deter- 
miner la  probabilite  des  evenemens  futurs  d'apres  ceux  qui  sont  deja 
arrives ;  mais  cette  matiere  etant  fort  etendue,  je  me  bornerai  ici  a 
donner  une  demonstration  assez  singuliere  du  theoreme  suivant. 

On  peut  suppose)'  les  nomhres  p  e^  q  tellement  grands,  qiuil  devienne 
aussi  ajJjirochant  que  Von  voudra  de  la  certitude,  que  le  rapport  du 
nomhre  de  billets  blancs  au  nomhre  total    des   billets    renfermes    dans 

Vurne,  est  compris  e^itre  les  deux  limites  — w,  et  — 1-  w,  to  pouvant 

p  +  qp-fq-^ 

etre  suj^j^ose  moindre  quaucune  grandeur  donnee. 

The  probability  of  the  ratio  lying  between  the  specified  limits  is 

x^{l  -xydx 


[ 


[  x^  (1  -  xy  dx 

^  0 

where  the  inteoral  in  the  numerator  is  to  be  taken  between  the 

limits  — w  and  — V «.     Laplace  by  a  rude  process   of 

^  +  ^  p-\-q 

30—2 


4G8  LAPLACE. 

approximation  arrives  at  tlie  conclusion  that  this  probability  does 
not  differ  much  from  unity. 

872.  Laplace  proceeds  to  the  Problem  of  Points.  He  quotes 
the  second  formula  which  we  have  given  in  Art.  172 ;  he  says  that 
it  is  now  demonstrated  in  several  works.  He  also  refers  to  his 
own  memoir  in  the  volume  of  the  Academy  for  1773 ;  he  adds 
the  followinof  statement  : 

...on  y  trouvera  pareillement  line  solution  generale  du  Problcme 
des  partis  dans  le  cas  de  trois  ou  d'un  plus  grand  nombre  de  joueurs, 
probleme  qui  n'a  eucore  ete  resolu  par  personno,  que  je  sache,  bien  que 
les  Geomutres  qui  ont  travaille  sui*  ces  matieres  en  aient  desire  la 
solution. 

Laplace  is  wrong  in  this  statement,  for  De  Moivre  had  solved 
the  problem  ;  see  Art.  582. 

873.  Let  X  denote  the  skill  of  the  player  A,  and  1—x  the  skill 
of  the  player  B ;  suppose  that  A  wants  f  games  in  order  to  win 
the  match,  and  that  B  wants  h  games  :  then,  if  they  agree  to  leave 
off  and  divide  the  stakes,  the  share  of  B  will  be  a  certain  quan- 
tity which  we  may  denote  by  (j)  {x,f,  h).  Suppose  the  skill  of  each 
2)layer  unhioiun;  let  7i  be  the  whole  number  of  games  which  A  or 
B  ought  to  win  in  order  to  entitle  him  to  the  stake.  Then  Laplace 
says  that  it  follows  from  the  general  principle  which  we  have  given 
in  Art.  869,  that  the  share  of  B  is 


I  ic"'-^  (1  -  x)""-^  (f)  (x,  f,  h)  clx 


J  0 


1 

x""'^  {y  -  xY^  dx 


The  formula  depends  on  the  fact  that  A  must  already  have 
won  n  —f  games,  and  B  have  won  n  —  li  games.     See  Art.  771. 

874.  Laplace  now  proceeds  to  the  question  of  the  mean  to  be 
taken  of  the  results  of  observations.  He  introduces  the  subject 
thus : 

On  peut,  au  moyen  de  la  Theorie  precedente,  parvenir  a  la  solution 
du  Problcme  qui  consiste  \  determiner  le  miUeu  que  Ton  doit  prendre 


LAPLACE.  469 

entre  plusieurs  observations  donnees  d'un  meme  phenomene.  II  j  a 
deux  ans  que  j'en  donnai  uue  a  1' Academic,  a  la  suite  du  Memoire  sur 
les  Series  recurrorecurrentes,  imi^rime  dans  ce  volume ;  mais  le  peu 
d'usage  dont  elle  pouvoit  etre,  me  la  fit  supprimer  lors  de  Timpression. 
J'ai  appris  depuis  par  le  Journal  astronomique  de  M,  Jean  Bernoulli, 
que  M".  Daniel  Bernoulli  et  la  Grange  se  sont  occupes  du  meme  pro- 
bleme  dans  deux  Memoires  manuscrits  qui  ne  sont  point  venus  a  ma 
connoissance.  Cette  annonce  jointe  a  I'utilite  de  la  matiere,  a  reveille 
mes  idees  sur  cet  objet ;  et  quoique  je  ne  doute  point  que  ces  deux 
illustres  Geometres  ne  Taient  traite  beaucoup  plus  heureusement  que 
raoi,  je  vais  cependant  exposer  ici  les  reflexions  qu'il  m'a  fait  naitre, 
persuade  que  les  differentes  manieres  dont  on  pent  I'envisager  j^roduiront 
une  methode  moins  hypothetiqiie  et  plus  sure  pour  determiner  le  milieu 
que  Ton  doit  prendre  entre  plusieurs  observations. 

875.  Laplace  then  enunciates  his  problem  thus  : 

Determiner  le  milieu  que  I'on  doit  prendre  entre  trois  observations 
donnees  d'un  meme  phenomene.  * 

Laplace  supposes  positive  and  negative  errors  to  be  equally 
likely,  and  he  takes  for  the  probability  that  an  error  lies  between 

X  and  x+  dx  the  expression  —  e~^^^  dx\  for  this  he  offers  some  rea- 

sons,  which  however  are  very  slight.  He  restricts  himself  as  his 
enunciation  states,  to  three  observations.  Thus  the  investigation 
cannot  be  said  to  have  any  practical  value. 

876.  Laplace  says  that  by  the  mean  which  ought  to  be  taken 
of  several  observations,  two  things  may  be  understood.  We  may 
understand  such  a  value  that  it  is  equally  likely  that  the  true 
value  is  above  or  below  it ;  this  he  says  we  may  call  the  milieu 
de  probdbilite.  Or  we  may  understand  such  a  value  that  the  sum 
of  the  errors,  each  multiplied  by  its  probability,  is  a  minimum ; 
this  he  says  we  may  call  the  milieu  derrein\  or  the  milieu  astro- 
nomique, as  being  that  which  astronomers  ought  to  adopt.  The 
errors  are  here  supposed  to  be  all  taken  positively. 

It  might  have  been  expected  from  Laplace's  words  that  these 
two  notions  of  a  mean  value  w^ould  lead  to  different  results  ;  he 
shews  however  that  they  lead  to  the  same  result.  In  both  cases 
the  mean  value  corresponds  to  the  point  at  which  the  ordinate  to 


470  LAPLACE. 

a  certain  curve  of  probability  bisects  the  area  of  the  curve.  See 
Theorie...des  Froh.  page  335. 

Laplace  does  not  notice  another  sense  of  the  word  mean, 
namely  an  average  of  all  the  values  ;  in  this  case  the  mean  would 
correspond  to  the  abscissa  of  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  area  of 
a  certain  curve.     See  Art.  485. 

877.  Laplace  now  proceeds  to  the  subject  which  is  considered 
in  Chapter  VIL  of  the  Theorie...des  Froh.,  namely  the  influence 
produced  by  the  want  of  perfect  symmetry  in  coins  or  dice  on  the 
chances  of  repetitions  of  events.  The  present  memoir  and  the 
Chapter  in  the  Theorie...des  Froh.  give  different  illustrations  of 
the  subject. 

The  first  case  in  the  memoir  is  that  of  the  Fetershurg  Fro- 
hlem,  though  Laplace  does  not  give  it  any  name.     Suppose  the 

chance  for  head  to  be  — ^ —  ,   and  therefore  the  chance  for  tail 

to  be   — ^^ —  ;  suppose  there  are  to  be  x  trials,  and  that  2  crowns 

are  to  be  received  if  head  appears  at  the  first  trial,  4  crowns  if 
head  does  not  appear  until  the  second  trial,  and  so  on.  Then  the 
expectation  is 

If  the  chance  for  head  is  — ^ — ,  and  therefore  the  chance  for 

tail  is  —^~ ,  we  must  change  the  sign  of  in-  in  the  expression  for 

the  expectation.  If  we  do  not  know  which  is  the  more  likelv  to 
appear,  head  or  tail,  we  may  take  half  the  sum  of  the  two  expres- 
sions for  the  expectation.     This  gives 

If  we  expand,  and  reject  powers  of  ot  higher  than  -cj^,  we  obtain 


LAPLACE.  .  471 

If  we  suppose  that  tis  may  have  any  value  between  0  and  c  we 
may  multiply  the  last  expression  by  d-us  and  integrate  from  0  to  c. 
See  Art.  529. 

878.     As   another  example   Laplace   considers   the   following 

question.    A  undertakes  to  throw  a  given  face  with  a  common  die 

in  n  throws  :  required  his  chance. 

/5\" 
If  the  die  be  perfectly  symmetrical  the  chance  is  1  —  i -j  ;  but 

if  the  die  be  not  perfectly  symmetrical  this  result  must  be 
modified.  Laplace  gives  the  investigation :  the  principle  is  the 
same  as  in  another  example  which  Laplace  also  gives,  and  to  which 
we  will  confine  ourselves.  Instead  of  a  common  die  with  six  faces 
we  will  suppose  a  triangular  prism  which  can  only  fall  on  one  of  its 
three  rectangular  faces :  required  the  probability  that  in  n  throws 
it  will  fall  on  an  assigned  face.  Let  the  chance  of  its  falling  on  the 

three  faces  be  — ^ — ,    — ^ —  and  — - —  respectively,  so  that 

'UJ  ■\-  "UJ    ■\- 'US     =0. 

Then  if  we  are  quite  ignorant  which  of  the  three  chances  belongs 
to  the  assigned  face,  we  must  suppose  in  succession  that  each  of 
them  does,  and  take  one-third  of  the  sum  of  the  results.  Thus  we 
obtain  one-third  of  the  following  sum, 


{ 


If  we  reject  powers  of  ■or,  tzr',  and  -ot"  beyond  the  square  we  get 
approximately 

«?«        n  (n  _  I)      9"-2 

3'' 1   2   '  •  3'^  '^     +tu-  +-57  ;. 

Suppose  we  know  nothing  about  ct,  ot',  and  ot",  except  that 
each  must  lie  between  —  c  and  +  c ;  we  wish  to  find  what  we  may 
call  the  average  value  of  ot^  -|-  tn-'^  -h  ts-''^ 

We  may  suppose  that  we  require  the  mean  value  of  x^  +  1^  -|-  z^, 


472  LAPLACE. 

subject  to  the  conditions  that  x  -\-  y  -{-  z  =  0,  and  that  x,  7/,  and  z 
must  each  lie  between  —  c  and  +  c. 
The  result  is 

J  oJ  -c 


"c  rc-x 


2  dxdij 


0. 


Laplace  works  out  this  result,  giving  the  reasons  for  the  steps 
briefly.  Geometrical  considerations  will  furnish  the  result  very 
readily.  We  may  consider  x  -^-y  ■\-z  =  ^  to  be  the  equation  to  a 
plane,  and  we  have  to  take  all  points  in  this  plane  lying  within 
a  certain  regular  hexagon.  The  projection  of  this  hexagon  on  the 
plane  of  {x,  y)  will  be  a  hexagon,  four  of  whose  sides  are  equal  to 
c,  and  the  other  two  sides  to  c\/2.     The  result  of  the  integration 

is  -  cl     Thus  the  chance  is 
b 


2"     n  {n  -  1)    2'^ 


-3 


3'^         1.2 


)n+2 


^      9 

DC  . 


879.  It  easily  follows  from  Laplace's  process  that  if  we  sup- 
pose a  coin  to  be  not  perfectly  symmetrical,  but  do  not  know 
whether  it  is  more  likely  to  give  head  or  tail,  then  the  chance  of 
two  heads  in  two  throws  or  the  chance  of  two  tails  in  two  throws 

is  rather  more  than  -  :  it  is  in  fact  equal  to  such  an  expression  as 


instead  of  being  equal  to  ^  x  ^ .     Laplace  after  adverting  to  this 

case  says, 

Cette  aberration  de  la  Thcorie  ordinaire,  qui  n'a  encore  ete  observee 
par  personne,  que  je  sache,  m'a  paru  digne  de  Fatten tion  des  Geometres, 
et  il  me  semble  que  Ton  ne  pent  trop  y  avoir  6gard,  lorsqu'on  applique 
le  calcul  des  probabilites,  aux  difTcrens  objets  de  la  vie  civile. 

880.  Scarcely  any  of  the  present  memoir  is  reproduced  by 
Laplace  in  his  Theorie...des  Proh.  Nearly  all  that  we  have  no- 
ticed in  our  account   of  the  memoir  u])  to  Art.  876  inclusive  is 


LAPLACE.  473 

indeed  superseded  by  Laplace's  later  researches;  but  what  we 
have  given  from  Art.  877  inclusive  might  have  appeared  in 
Chapter  VIL  of  the  Theorie...des  Prob. 

881.  Laplace's  next  memoir  on  our  subject  is  in  the  Memoires 
...par  divei^s Savans... 177 S',  the  date  of  publication  is  1776.  The 
memoir  is  entitled  Recherclies  sur  ^integration  des  Equations  dif- 
ferentielles  aux  differences  Jinies,  et  sur  leur  usage  dans  la  theorie 
des  hasards,  &c. 

The  portion  on  the  theory  of  chances  occupies  pages  113 — 163. 
Laplace  begins  with  some  general  observations.  He  refers  to  the 
subject  wdiich  he  had  already  discussed,  which  we  have  noticed 
in  Art.  877.  He  says  that  the  advantage  arising  from  the  w^ant 
of  symmetry  is  on  the  side  of  the  player  Avho  bets  that  head 
will  not  arrive  in  two  throws  :  this  follow^s  from  Art.  879  ;  for  to 
bet  that  head  will  not  arrive  in  two  throws  is  to  bet  that  both 
throws  will  give  tail. 

882.  The  first  problem  he  solves  is  that  of  odd  and  even;  see 
Art.  865. 

The  next  problem  is  an  example  of  Compound  Interest,  and 
has  nothing  connected  with  probability. 

The  next  problem  is  as  follows.  A  solid  has  p  equal  faces, 
which  are  numbered  1,  2,...^:?:  required  the  probability  that  in 
the  course  of  n  throws  the  faces  will  occur  in  the  order  ],  2,...^. 

This  j)roblem  is  nearly  the  same  as  that  about  a  run  of  events 
Avhich  w^e  have  reproduced  from  De  Moivre  in  Art.  325 :  instead 
of  the  equation  there  given  we  have 

^'n+i  =  ^n  +  (1  -  ^n^i-p)  «";  whcre  a  =  -  . 

883.  The  next  problem  is  thus  enunciated : 

Je  suppose  un  nombre  n  de  joueiirs  (1),  (2),  (3),  ...  (?/),  jouant  de 
cette  maniere ;  (1)  joue  avec  (2),  et  s'il  gagne  il  gagne  la  partie ;  s'il  ne 
perd  ni  gagne,  il  continue  de  jouer  avec  (2),  jusqu'a  ce  que  I'un  des 
deux  gagne.  Que  si  (1)  perd,  (2)  joue  avec  (3) ;  s'il  le  gagne,  il  gagne  la 
partie ;  s'il  ne  perd  ni  gagne,  il  continue  de  jouer  avec  (3) ;  mais  s'il 
perd,  (3)  joue  avec  (4),  et  ainsi  de  suite  jusqu'a  ce  que  I'un  des  joueurs 
ait  vaincu  celui  qui  le  suit;  c'est-a-dire  que  (1)  soit  vainqueur  de  (2), 


47^  LAPLACE. 

ou  (2)  de  (3),  ou  (3)  de  (4),  ...  on  (n-1)  de  (71),  ou  (n)  de  (1).    Be  plus, 
la  probabilite  d'lin  quelconque  des  joueurs,  pour  gagner  I'autre  =^,  et 

celle  de  ne  gagner  ni  perdre  =^.     Cela  pose,  il  faut  determiner  la  pro- 

babilite  que  Tun  de  ces  joueurs  gagnera  la  partie  au  coup  x. 

This  problem  is  rather  difficult;  it  is  not  reproduced  in  the 
Theorie...des  Proh.  The  following  is  the  general  result:  Let  v^ 
denote  the  chance  that  any  assigned  player  will  win.  the  match 
at  the  ic*^^  trial ;  then 

n  n  {n  —  1")  1  n  [n  —  1)  {n  —  2)  1 

'^x         o  ^x-\  "T  -j     4>  q^   ^X-2         '  -j      9     O  03    ^X-^     I     •  •  • 

1 

syii  ^x—n' 

884^.  Laplace  next  takes  the  Problem  of  Points  in  the  case 
of  two  players,  and  then  the  same  problem  in  the  case  of  three 
players ;  see  Art.  872.  Laplace  solves  the  problem  by  Finite  Differ- 
ences. At  the  beginning  of  the  volume  which  contains  the  memoir 
some  errata  are  corrected,  and  there  is  also  another  solution  indi- 
cated of  the  Pr^^blem  of  Points  for  three  players;  this  solution 
depends  on  the  expansion  of  a  multinomial  exj^ression,  and  is 
in  fact  identical  with  that  which  had  been  given  by  De  Moivre. 

Laplace's  next  problem  may  be  considered  an  extension  of  the 
Problem  of  Points;  it  is  reproduced  in  the  Theorie...des  Proh. 
page  214,  beginning  with  the  words  Concevons  encore. 

885.  The  next  two  problems  are  on  the  Duration  of  Play;  in 
the  first  case  the  capitals  being  equal,  and  in  the  second  case 
unequal;  see  Art.  8G3.  The  solutions  are  carried  further  than  in 
the  former  memoir,  but  they  are  still  much  inferior  to  those 
which  were  subsequently  given  in  the  TIieor{e...des  Proh. 

886.  The  next  problem  is  an  extension  of  the  problem  of 
Duration  of  Play  with  equal  capitals. 

It  is  supposed  that  at  every  game  there  is  the  chance  ^?  for 
A,  the  chance  q  for  J3,  and  the  chance  r  that  neither  wins;  each 
player  has  m  crowns  originally,  and  the  loser  in  any  game  gives 
a  crown  to  the  winner :  required  the  probability  that  the  play 
will  be  finished  in  x  games.  This  problem  is  not  reproduced  in 
the  Theorie...des  Proh. 


LAPLACE.  475 

887.  The  present  memoir  may  be  regarded  as  a  collection  of 
examples  in  the  theory  of  Finite  Differences ;  the  methods  ex- 
emplified have  however  since  been  superseded  by  that  of  Gene- 
rating Functions,  which  again  may  be  considered  to  have  now 
given  w^ay  to  the  Calculus  of  Operations.  The  problems  involve 
only  questions  in  direct  probability ;  none  of  them  involve  what 
are  called  questions  in  inverse  probability,  that  is,  questions 
respecting  the  probability  of  causes  as  deduced  from  observed 
events. 

888.  In  the  same  volume  as  the  memoir  we  have  just  ana- 
lysed there  is  a  memoir  by  Laplace  entitled,  Menioire  sur  Tincli' 
naison  moyenne  des  orbites  des  cometes ;  sur  la  figure  de  la  Terre, 
et  sur  les  Fonctions.  The  part  of  the  memoir  devoted  to  the  mean 
inclination  of  the  orbits  of  comets  occupies  pages  503 — 524  of  the 
volume. 

In  these  pages  Laplace  discusses  the  problem  which  was  started 
by  Daniel  Bernoulli ;  see  Art.  395.  Laplace's  result  agrees  wdth 
that  which  he  afterwards  obtained  in  the  Theorie...des  Proh. 
pages  253 — 260,  but  the  method  is  quite  different ;  both  methods 
are  extremely  laborious. 

Laplace  gives  a  numerical  example ;  he  finds  that  supposing 
12  comets  or  planets  the  chance  is  "339  that  the  mean  inclination 
of  the  planes  of  the  orbits  to  a  fixed  plane  will  lie  betw^een 
45°  —  7^"  and  45",  and  of  course  the  chance  is  the  same  that  the 
mean  inclination  wiJl  lie  between  45"^  and  45^  +  7^°. 


889.  The  volume  with  which  w^e  have  been  eno^aofed  in  Arti- 
cles  881 — 888  is  remarkable  in  connexion  with  Physical  Astronomy. 
Historians  of  this  subject  usually  record  its  triumphs,  but  omit  its 
temporary  failures.  In  the  present  volume  Lagrange  affects  to 
shew  that  the  secular  acceleration  of  the  Moon's  motion  cannot  be 
explained  by  the  ordinary  theory  of  gravitation ;  and  Laplace 
affects  to  shew  that  the  inequalities  in  the  motions  of  Jupiter  and 
Saturn  cannot  be  attributed  to  the  mutual  action  of  these  planets : 
see  pages  47,  213  of  the  volume.  Laplace  lived  to  correct  both  his' 
rival's  error  and  his  own,  by  two  of  his  greatest  contributions  to 
Physical  Astronomy. 


476  LAPLACE. 

890.  Laplace's  next  memoir  on  our  subject  is  entitled  Me- 
vioire  sur  les  Prohahilites ;  it  is  contained  in  the  volume  for  1778 
of  the  Histoire  de  l Acad.... Paris:  the  date  of  publication  of  the 
volume  is  1781.     The  memoir  occupies  pages  227 — 382. 

In  the  notice  of  the  memoir  which  is  given  in  the  introductory 
part  of  the  volume  the  names  of  Bayes  and  Price  are  mentioned. 
Laplace  does  not  allude  to  them  in  the  memoir.     See  Art.  540. 

891.  Laplace  begins  with  remarks,  similar  to  those  which  we 
have  already  noticed,  respecting  the  chances  connected  with  the 
tossing  of  a  coin  which  is  not  quite  symmetrical;  see  Arts.  877, 881. 
He  solves  the  simple  problem  of  Duration  of  Play  in  the  way  we 
have  given  in  Art.  107.  Thus  let  p  denote  A's  skill,  and  1  —p  de- 
note ^'s  skill.  Suppose  A  to  start  with  m  stakes,  and  B  to  start 
with  n  —  m  stakes  :  then  ^'s  chance  of  winning  all  ^'s  stakes  is 

P^-ii-pY     ' 

1  1 

Laplace  puts  for  p  in  succession  -  (1  +  a)  and  «  (1  ~  ^)>  ^^^ 
takes  half  the  sum.     Thus  he  obtains  for  ^'s  chance 

|{(l  +  a)"-+(l-a)"-"j{(l+ar-(l-ar} 

(1  +  ay  -  (1  -  a)"  ' 

which  he  transforms  into 


1    ln_a=)™  (!  +  «)""'"'- (!-«)" 


-2m 


2      2^        ^         (l+a)"-(l-a)'' 

oil 
The  expression  for  ^'s  chance  becomes  —  when  a  vanishes ; 

Laplace  proposes  to  shew  that  the  expression  increases  as  a  in- 
creases, if  2m  be  less  than  ??.  The  factor  (1  —  a^)""  obviously  dimin- 
ishes as  a  increases.  Laplace  says  that  if  2m  is  less  than  n  it  is 
clear  that  the  fraction 

(I  +  ay -{I -ay 


LAPLACE.  477 

also  diminishes  as  a  increases.     We  will  demonstrate  tliis. 
Put  r  for  w  —  2m,  and  denote  the  fraction  by  u ;  then 

idu^  (1  +  cr'  +  (1  -  ay      (1  +  ay-'  +  (1  -  cy-' 

uda     ''    {l+OLy-{l-ay        ^     (l  +  a)"-(l-a)"     * 
Thus 

where  2;  =  :j .     We  have  to  shew  that  this  expression  is  nega- 

tive  :  this  we   shall  do  by  shewino^  that  -~. — :i — "^  increases  as 

successive  integral  values  are  ascribed  to  r.     We  have 

(r  +  1)  (3^+1)      r{z'-'+l) 
z'^'  -  1  z'-\ 

_  (r  +  1)  (/'  -l)-r  (z^'  -  1)  (z^-'  +  1)  ^ 
{z""^' -  1)  {z' -  1)  ' 

thus  we  must  shew  that  z^""  —  1  is  greater  than  r  {z'^^^  —  z""^). 

Expand  by  the  exponential  theorem  ;  then  we  find  we  have  to 
shew  that 

{2ry  is  gi-eater  than  r  |  (r  +  1)^  -  (r  -  1)^  I  , 

where  ^  is  any  positive  integer ;  that  is,  we  must  shew  that 
2i>-i  ,J'-i  is  greater  than ^r"''  4- i^  (/^  ~  ^H/>  -  ^)  ^,^-3  _^  ^^^ 

But  this  is  obvious,  for  r  is  supposed  greater  than  unity,  and 
the  two  members  would  be  equal  if  all  the  exponents  of  r  on  the 
right  hand  side  of  the  inequality  were^  —  1. 

We  observe  that  r  must  be  supposed  not  less  than  2 ;  if  r  =  1 
we  have  s'^'"  —  1  =  7-  (s*^^  —  s*^^). 

We  have  assumed  that  r  and  n  are  integers,  and  this  limitation 
is  necessary.     For  return  to  the  expression 

(1  +  a)' -  (1  -  a)' 


(1  +  a)"  -{\-a) 


n  J 


478  LAPLACE. 

and  put  for  a  in  succession  0  and  1 ;  then  we  have  to  compare  -  with 

71 

2  .  v      .       n  ,        X 

^  ;  that  is,  we  have  to  compare  t-  with  —  .     Now  consider  —  ;  the 

differential  coefficient  with  respect  to  x  is ^^ —  ;  so  that  -^ 

increases  as   x   changes   from   0  to    , — - ,  and  then  diminishes. 

*  log  2 ' 

Laplace  treats  the  same  question  in  the  Theorie...des  Proh. 
page  406  ;  there  also  the  difficulty  is  dismissed  with  the  words  il 
est  facile  de  voir.  In  the  memoir  prefixed  to  the  fourth  volume  of 
Bowditch's  Translation  of  the  Mecanique  Celeste,  page  62,  we  read : 

Dr  Bowditch  himself  was  accustomed  to  remark,  "  Whenever  I  meet 
in  La  Place  with  the  words  '  Thus  it  plainly  appears'  I  am  sure  that 
hours,  and  perhaps  days  of  hard  study  will  alone  enable  me  to  discover 
how  it  plainly  appears." 

892.  The  pages  240 — 258  of  the  memoir  contain  the  im- 
portant but  difficult  investigation  which  is  reproduced  in  the 
Theorie...des  Proh.  pages  262 — 272.  Laplace  gives  in  the  memoir 
a  reference  to  those  investigations  by  Lagrange  which  we  have 
noticed  in  Art.  570  ;  the  reference  however  is  omitted  in  the 
Theorie...des  Proh. 

893.  Laplace  now  proceeds  to  the  subject  which  he  had  con- 
sidered in  a  former  memoir,  namely,  the  probability  of  causes  as 
deduced  from  events;  see  Art.  868.  Laplace  repeats  the  general 
principle  which  he  had  already  enunciated  in  his  former  memoir; 
see  Art.  869.  He  then  takes  the  problem  which  we  have  noticed 
in  Art.  870,  enunciating  it  however  with  respect  to  the  births  of 
boys  and  girls,  instead  of  the  drawings  of  white  and  black  balls. 
See  Art.  770. 

894.  Laplace  is  now  led  to  consider  the  approximate  evalu- 
ation of  definite  integrals,  and  he  gives  the  method  which  is  repro- 
duced almost  identically  in  pages  88 — 90  of  the  Theorie.,.des  Proh. 

He  applies  it  to  the  example  x^(l—xydx,  and  thus  demon- 
strates the  theorem  he  had  already  given ;  see  Art.  871 :  the  pre- 
sent demonstration  is  much  superior  to  the  former. 


LAPLACE.  479 

895.     There  is  one  proposition  given  here  which  is  not  repro- 
duced in  the  Theorie...des  Proh.,  but  which  is  worthy  of  notice. 

Suppose  we  require   the  value  of  \ydx  where  y  =  x^  {\  —  oc-y, 
the  integral  being  taken  between  assigned  limits. 

Put  2^—  ^  ^^^  2' ~     '  ^^^^  ^^^ 


a  "a 


1      r7x 


Then,  by  integrating  by  parts, 

lydx=  \uzdy  =  c,?/^  — a  lydz (1), 

f   7  f  dz    y  dz         [     d   [   dz\  , 

so  that 

/y^x  =  «^.-a>|+./j;yi  (.J)^..  (2). 

Now  y  vanishes  with  x.     Laplace  shews  that   the   value   of 
\ydx  when  the  lower  limit  is  zero  and  the  upper  limit  is  any 

value  of  X  less  than ,  is  less  than  cyz  and  is  fjreater  than 

1  +  /A  ^  * 

dz 
ayz  —  o?yz  — -;  so  that  we  can  test  the  closeness  of  the  approxi- 

mation.     This   proposition   depends    on  the   following  considera- 

dz   .  .  .  1 

tions :  -^  is  positive  so  long  as  x  is  less  than ,  and  there- 

fore   \ydx  is  less  than  c.yz  by  (1);  and  —  [^ -f)  is  also  jDositive, 

r  dz 

so  that  \ydx  is  greater  than  o.yz  —  (^yz  -^  by  (2).     For  we  have 

a?  (1  —  cr) 


z  = 


l-(l+yu)a;' 
and  this  can  be  put  in  the  form 


480  LAPLACE. 


Lb  X  Lb 

^  =  -7^-^.+  . -7--  + 


dz 
Hence  we  see  that  z  and    -^  both  increase  with  x  so  long 

as  X  is  less  than :  this  establishes  the  required  proposition. 

See  also  Art.  767. 

896.  Laplace  then  takes  the  following  problem.  In  26  years 
it  was  observed  in  Paris  that  251527  boys  were  born  and  241945 
girls  :    required  the  probability  that  the  j^ossibility  of  the  birth 

of  a  boy  is  greater  than  -^ .     The  probability  is  found  to  differ 

from  unity  by  less  than  a  fraction  having  for  its  numerator  1*1521 
and  for  its  denominator  the  seventh  power  of  a  million. 

This  problem  is  reproduced  in  the  Theorie...des  Pi^oh.  pages 
877 — 380,  the  data  being  the  numbers  of  births  during  40  years 
instead  of  during  26  years. 

897.  Taking  the  same  data  as  in  the  preceding  Article,  La- 
place investigates  the  probability  that  in  a  given  year  the  number 
of   boys  born  shall  not  exceed  the  number  of  girls   born.     He 

1 

finds    the    probability    to    be    a    little    less   .than    ^—^  .      The 

result  of  a  similar  calculation  from  data  furnished  by  observations 

in  London  is  a  little  less  than  t^^tzti  .     In  pa<?es  397 — 401  of  the 

12410  ^   ° 

Theorie...des  Prob.  we  have  a  more  difficult  problem,  namely  to 
find  the  probability  that  during  a  century  the  annual  births  of 
boys  shall  never  be  less  than  that  of  girls.  The  treatment  of 
the  simpler  problem  in  the  memoir  differs  from  that  of  the 
more  difficult  problem  in  the  Theorie...des  Froh.  In  the  memoir 
Laplace  obtains  an  equation  in  Finite  Differences 

hence  he  deduces 

%m=  constant  -f  ?/,„.^,„_,  |l  -  A^^,„_2  +  A  {z,,,_^i^z^,,_^ 


LAPLACE.  481 

which  as  he  says  is  analogous  to  the  corresponding  theorem  in 
the  Integral  Calculus  given  in  Art.  895  ;  and,  as  in  that  Article,  he 
shews  that  in  the  problem  he  is  discussing  the  exact  result  lies 
between  two  approximate  results.     See  also  Art.  770. 

898.  The  memoir  contains  on  page  287  a  brief  indication  of  a 
problem  which  is  elaborately  treated  in  pages  369 — 376  of  the 
TJi eo rie . . .  cles  P) 'ob. 

899.  Laplace  now  developes  another  form  of  his  method  of 
approximation  to  the  value   of  definite   integrals.     Suppose  we 

require  lydx;    let    Y  be   the   maximum  value   of  ?/   within  the 

range  of  the  integration.     Assume   ?/  =  Ye~^\    and  thus   change 

li/dx    into   an  integi'al  with  respect  to   t.     The  investigation  is 

reproduced  in  the  Theor{e...des  Frob.  pages  101 — 103. 

n  00 

Laplace  determines  the  value  of  /    e~^'dt.     He  does  this  by 

taking  the  double  integral  /  e'^^^-^^'^dsdu,  and  equating  the 

results   which   are   obtained  by  considering   the   integrations   in 
different  orders. 

900.  Laplace  also  considers  the  case  in  which  instead  of  as- 
suming y  =  Fe"*^^,  we  may  assume  y  =  Ye~^.  Something  similar  is 
given  in  the  TJieorie...des  Proh.  pages  93 — 95. 

Some  formulae  occur  in  the  memoir  which  are  not  reproduced 
in  the  Theorie...des  Proh.,  and  which  are  quite  wrong:  we  will 
point  out  the  error.  Laplace  says  on  pages  298,  299  of  the 
memoir : 

,      ,     , ,     .  -iff       d.c  dz 

Considerons  presentement  la  double  integrale    1 1 ■- —3,  prise 

;y  (1  -z  -x^'Y 

depuis  a:  =  0   jusqu'a  £c  =  l,   et  depiiis    z  =  ^   jusqu'a    ^=1;  en  faisant 

X  ,      „  ,  ,  .    [      dz        [      dx 

,=x,  elle  se  cnano;era  dans    ce.le-ci    /-— / —  ,  ces 

(l-z')^  Jj{l-z')J{l-x")i 

integrales  etant  prises  depuis  x'  -0  et  ;^  -  0,  ju^-qu'a  x'  —1  et  z=l,    

31 


482  LAPLACE. 

Then,  as  ,,.,  ""    .,,  =  ^  ,  Laplace  infers  that 

r  r       dxch         _'TT  f'       dx 

Bat  this  is  wrono^ ;  for  the  limits  of  x  are  0  and 7 ,  and 

°  (1  -  £y 

not  0  and  1,  as  Laplace  says  ;  and  so  the  process  fails. 

Laplace  makes  the   same   mistake  again   immediately  after- 
wards  ;  he  puts   -jj^ -^  —  z\  and  thus  deduces 


I 


dxdz  [^      dx        [^      dz 


J„  (1  _ ^^  _  ^^)i    J,  (1  _  x^)k!,  (1  _ ^-)t  • 

But  the  upper  limit  for  z   should  be  -j-Fx — ~T\  >    ^^^  ^^^  ^  ^^ 

'Y  (  X        X  j 

Laplace  assumes ;  and  so  the  process  fails. 

901.  -Laplace  applies  his  method  to  evaluate  approximately 

I   a?^  (1  —  xY  dx ;   and  he  finds  an  opportunity  for  demonstrating 

•J  0 

Stirling's  Theorem.     See  Art.  333. 

902.  Laplace  discusses  in  pages  304 — 313  of  the  memoir  the 
following  problem.  Observation  shews  that  the  ratio  of  the  num- 
ber of  births  of  boys  to  that  of  girls  is  sensibly  greater  at  London 
than  at  Paris  ;  this  seems  to  indicate  a  greater  facility  for  the  birth 
of  a  boy  at  London  than  at  Paris :  required  to  determine  the 
amount  of  probability.     See  Art.  773. 

Let  w  be  the  probability  of  the  birth  of  a  boy  at  Paris,  p  the 
number  of  births  of  boys  observed  there,  and  q  the  number  of  births 
of  girls  ;  let  z^  —  ic  be  the  possibility  of  the  birth  of  a  boy  at  Lon- 
don, p  the  number  of  births  of  boys  observed  there,  and  q  the 
number  of  births  of  girls.  If  P  denote  the  probability  that  the 
birth  of  a  boy  is  less  possible  at  London  than  at  Paris,  we  have 

{U  (1  _  uy  {u - xY  (1-U  +  xY du dx 


P  = 


\ie  (1  -  uY  {u  -  xY  (1  -  M  +  xY  die  dx 


LAPLACE.  483 

Laplace  says  that  the  integral  in  the  numerator  is  to  be  taken 
from  ic  =  0  to  u  =  x,  and  from  a?  =  0  to  ic  =  1,  and  that  the  integral 
in  the  denominator  is  to  be  taken  for  all  possible  values  of  x  and  ii. 
Thus  putting  u  —  x  =  s  the  denominator  becomes 


[    [  u''  (1  -  u)'  s^'  (1  -  sY  du  ds. 

•J  {^    ■J  Q 


Laplace's  statement  of  the  limits  for  the  numerator  is  wrong ; 
we  should  integrate  for  x  from  0  to  u,  and  then  for  u  from  0  to  1. 

There  is  also  another  mistake.     Laplace  has  the  equation 

V_ £_    ,JP_ l__  =  n 

X      l-X'^X-x     l-X-^x 

He  finds  correctly  that  when  a?  =  0  this  gives 


X  = 


jy+p 


He  says  that  when  jr  =  1  it  gives  X  =  l,  which  is  wrong. 

Laplace  however  really  uses  the  right  limits  of  integration  in 
his  work.  His  solution  is  very  obscure  ;  it  is  put  in  a  much  clearer 
form  in  a  subsequent  memoir  which  we  shall  presently  notice  ;  see 
Art.  909.     He  uses  the  following  values, 

p  =  251527,     q  =  24.1945, 
;/=  737629,    ^'  =  698958, 

and  he  obtains  in  the  present  memoir 

410458  ' 
he  obtains  in  the  subsequent  memoir 

1 


P  = 


410178* 


The  problem  is  also  solved  in  the  Theorie . . .  des  Proh.  pages 
381 — 384  ;  the  method  there  is  different  and  free  from  the  mis- 
takes which  occur  in  the  memoir.  Laplace  there  uses  values  of  p 
and  q  derived  from  longer  observations,  namely 

.     ^  =  393386,  ^=377555; 

31—2 


484  LAPLACE. 

he  retains  the  same  vakies  oip  and  q  as  before,  and  he  obtains 

1 


P  = 


328269  • 


It  will  be  seen  that  the  new  values  of  p  and  q  make  -  a  little 

larger  than  the  old  values  ;  hence  it  is  natural  that  P  should  be 
increased. 

903.  Laplace  gives  in  the  memoir  some  important  investiga- 
tions on  the  probability  of  future  events  as  deduced  from  ob- 
served events;  these  are  reproduced  in  the  Theorie . . . des  Proh. 
pages  394—396. 

904.  Laplace  devotes  the  last  ten  pages  of  his  memoir  to 
the  theory  of  errors ;  he  says  that  after  his  memoir  in  the  sixth 
volume  of  the  Memoires...par  divers  Savans  the  subject  had  been 
considered  by  Lagrange,  Daniel  Bernoulli  and  Euler.  Since,  how- 
ever, their  principles  differed  from  his  own  he  is  induced  to  resume 
the  investigation,  and  to  present  his  results  in  such  a  manner  as  to 
leave  no  doubt  of  their  exactness.  Accordingly  he  gives,  with 
some  extension,  the  same  theory  as  before  ;  see  Art.  874.  The 
theory  does  not  seem,  however,  to  have  any  great  value. 

905.  The  present  memoir  deserves  to  be  regarded  as  very  im- 
portant in  the  history  of  the  subject.  The  method  of  approxima- 
tion to  the  values  of  definite  integrals,  which  is  here  expounded, 
must  be  esteemed  a  great  contribution  to  mathematics  in  general 
and  to  our  special  department  in  particular.  The  applications 
made  to  the  problems  respecting  births  shew  the  power  of  the 
method  and  its  peculiar  value  in  the-  theory  of  probability. 

906.  Laplace's  next  memoir  on  our  subject  is  entitled  Memoir e 
sur  les  Suites;  it  is  published  in  the  volume  for  1779  of  the 
Histoire  de  l' A  cad... Paris;  the  date  of  publication  is  1782.  The 
memoir  occupies  pages  207 — 809  of  the  volume. 

This  memoir  contains  the  theory  of  Generating  Functions. 
With  the  exception  of  pages  269 — 286  the  whole  memoir  is 
reproduced  almost  identically  in  the  T}ieorie..,des  Proh.;  it  forms 
pages  9 — 80  of  the  work.      The  pages  which  are  not  reproduced 


LAPLACE.  4S5 

relate   to    tlie   solution   of  partial   differential   equations   of   the 
second  order,  and  have  no  connexion  with  our  subject. 

The  formulae  which  occur  at  the  top  of  pages  18  and  19  of 
the  Theorie...des  Proh.  are  stated  in  the  memoir  to  agree  with 
those  which  had  been  given  in  Newton's  Methodus  differentialis ; 
this  reference  is  omitted  in  the  TJieorie...des  Proh. 

907.  Laplace's  next  memoir  on  our  subject  is  entitled  ^itr  les 
approximations  des  Formides  qui  sont  fonctions  de  tres-grands  nom- 
hres;  it  is  published  in  the  volume  for  1782  of  the  Histoire  de 
V Acad... Paris:  the  date  of  publication  is  1785.  The  memoir 
occupies  pages  1 — 88  of  the  volume. 

Laplace  refers  at  the  commencement  to  the  evaluation  of 
the  middle  coefficient  of  a  binomial  raised  to  a  high  power  by 
the  aid  of  Stirling's  Theorem  ;  Laplace  considers  this  to  be  one 
of  the  most  ingenious  discoveries  which  had  been  made  in  the 
theory  of  Series.  His  object  in  the  memoir  is  to  effect  similar 
transformations  for  other  functions  involving  large  numbers,  in 
order  that  it  might  be  practicable  to  calculate  the  numerical 
values  of  such  functions. 

The  memoir  is  reproduced  without  any  important  change 
in  the  T]ieorie...des  Proh.,  in  which  it  occupies  pages  88 — 171-. 
See  Arts.  89-i,  899. 

A  mistake  occurs  at  the  beginning  of  page  29  of  the  memoir, 
and  extends  its  influence  to  the  end  of  page  30.  Suppose  that  a 
function  of  two  independent  variables,  6  and  6',  is  to  be  exjDanded 
in  powers  of  these  variables:  we  may  denote  the  terms  of  the 
second  degree  by  Md^ +  2N96'+ P6"^ :  Laplace's  mistake  amounts 
to  omitting  the  term  2X66'.  The  mistake  does  not  occur  in  the 
corresponding  passage  on  page  108  of  the  Tlieorie...des  Proh. 

908.  Laplace's  next  memoii*  is  the  continuation  of  the  pre- 
ceding; it  is  entitled,  Suite  du  Memoire  sur  les  approximations 
des  Formides  qui  sont  fonctions  de  tres-grands  Komhres;  it  is  pub- 
lished in  the  volume  for  1783  of  the  Histoire  de  V Acad... Paris: 
the  date  of  publication  is  1786.  The  memoir  occupies  pages 
423 — 467  of  the  volume. 

909.  Laplace  gives  here  some  matter  which  is  reproduced  in 
the  Theorie.., des  Proh.  pages  363—365,  394—396.  Pages  440—444 


486  LAPLACE. 

of  the  memoir  are  not  reproduced  in  the  Theorie , . .des  Proh.; 
they  depend  partly  on  those  pages  of  the  memoir  of  1782  which 
are  erroneous,  as  we  saw  in  Art.  907. 

Laplace  in  this  memoir  applies  his  formulae  of  approxima- 
tion to  the  solution  of  questions  in  probability.  See  Arts.  767,  769. 
He  takes  the  problem  which  we  have  noticed  in  Art.  896,  and 
arrives  at  a  result  practically  coincident  with  the  former.  He  takes 
the  problem  which  we  have  noticed  in  Art.  902,  gives  a  much 
better  investigation,  and  arrives  at  a  result  practically  coincident 
with  the  former.  He  solves  the  problem  about  the  births  during  a 
century  to  which  we  have  referred  in  Art.  897,  using  the  smaller 
values  of  j9  and  q  which  we  have  given  in  Art.  902;  he  finds 
the  required  probability  to  be  "664.  In  the  Theorie...des  Proh. 
page  401  he  uses  the  larger  values  of  j)  and  q  which  we  have 
given  in  Art.  902,  and  obtains  for  the  required  probability  "782. 

910.  This  memoir  also  contains  a  calculation  respecting  a 
lottery  which  is  reproduced  in  the  Theo7'ie...des  Proh.  page  195. 
See  Arts.  455,  864. 

Laplace  suggests  on  page  433  of  the  memoir  that  it  would 

be  useful  to  form  a  table  of  the  value  of  \e~^'dt  for  successive 
limits  of  the  integration  :  such  a  table  we  now  possess. 

911.  In  the  same  volume  there  is  another  memoir  by  La- 
place which  is  entitled,  Sur  les  naissances,  les  mcwiages  et  les 
marts  d  Paris....  This  memoir  occupies  pages  693 — 702  of  the 
volume. 

The  following  problem  is  solved.  Suppose  we  know  for  a 
large  country  like  France  the  number  of  births  in  a  year  ;  and 
suppose  that  for  a  certain  district  we  know  both  the  population 
and  the  number  of  births.  If  we  assume  that  the  ratio  of  the 
population  to  the  number  of  births  in  a  year  is  the  same  for  the 
whole  country  as  it  is  for  the  district,  we  can  determine  the  popu- 
lation of  the  whole  country.  Laplace  investigates  the  probability 
that  the  error  in  the  result  will  not  exceed  an  assiofned  amount. 
He  concludes  from  his  result  that  the  district  ouo'ht  to  contain 
not  less  than  a  million  of  people  in  order  to  obtain  a  sufficient 
accuracy  in  the  number  of  the  population  of  France. 


LAPLACE.  487 

The  problem  is  reproduced  in  tlie  Theorie...des  Proh.  pages 
391 — 39-i.  The  necessary  observations  were  made  by  the  Frencb 
government  at  Laplace's  request ;  the  population  of  the  district 
selected  was  a  little  more  than  two  millions. 

The  solutions  of  the  problem  in  the  memoir  and  in  the 
Theorie. .  .des  Proh.  are  substantially  the  same. 

912.  In  the  Lecons  de  Mathematiques  donnees  a  Tecole  normale, 
en  1795,  par  M.  Laplace,  we  have  one  le^on  devoted  to  the  subject 
of  probabilities.  The  legons  are  given  in  the  Journal  de  VEcole 
Poly  technique  y  vii^  et  viii®  cahiers,  1812;  but  we  may  infer  from 
page  164  that  there  had  been  an  earlier  publication.  The  lecon 
on  probabilities  occupies  pages  140 — 172.  It  is  a  popular  state- 
ment of  some  of  the  results  which  had  been  obtained  in  the 
subject,  and  was  expanded  by  Laplace  into  the  Introduction 
which  appeared  with  the  second  edition  of  the  Theorie.,. des  Proh., 
as  he  himself  states  at  the  beginning  of  the  Introduction. 

913.  With  the  exception  of  the  unimportant  matter  noticed 
in  the  preceding  Ai'ticle,  Laplace  seems  to  have  left  the  Theory 
of  Probability  untouched  for  more  than  twenty-five'^years.  His 
attention  was  probably  fully  engaged  in  embodying  his  own  re- 
searches and  those  of  other  astronomers  in  his  Mecanique  Celeste, 
the  first  four  volumes  of  which  appeared  between  1798  and  1805. 

914.  Laplace's  next  memoir  connected  with  the  Theory  of 
Probability  is  entitled  Memoire  sur  les  approximations  des  for- 
mules  qui  sont  fonctions  de  tres-grands  nomhres,  et  sur  leur  ap- 
plication aux  prohoMlites.  This  memoir  is  published  in  the 
Memoires...de  VInstitut  for  1809;  the  date  of  publication  is  1810 ; 
the  memoir  occupies  pages  353 — 415  of  the  volume,  and  a  supj^le- 
ment  occupies  pages  559 — oQo. 

915.  The  first  subject  which  is  discussed  is  the  problem  re- 
lating to  the  inclination  of  the  orbits  of  the  planets  and  comets 
which  is  given  in  the  Theorie... des  Proh.  pages  253 — 261;  see 
also  Art.  888.  The  mode  of  discussion  is  nearly  the  same.  [There 
is  however  some  difference  in  the  jDrocess  relating  to  i\iQ  planets, 
for  in  the  memoir  Laplace  takes  two  right  angles  as  the  extreme 


488  LAPLACE. 

angle  instead  of  one  right  angle  whicli  he  takes  in  the  Tlieorle... 
des  Prob.     Laplace's  words  are,  on  page  362  of  the  memoir  : 

Si  Ton  fait  varier  les  inclinaisons  depuis  zero  jiisqu'a  la  demi-cir- 
conference,  on  fait  disparoitre  la  consideration  des  mouvemens  retro- 
grades j  car  le  mouvement  direct  se  change  ^en  retrograde,  quand  I'incli- 
naison  surpasse  un  angle  droit. 

Laplace  obtains  in  the  memoir  the  same  numerical  result  as  on 
page  258  of  the  Theorie...des  Proh. ;  but  in  the  latter  place  the 
fact  of  the  motions  being  all  in  the  same  direction  is  expressly 
used,  while  in  the  former  place  Laplace  implies  that  this  fact  still 
remains  to  be  considered. 

The  calculation  for  the  comets,  which  follows  some  investiga- 
tions noticed  in  the  next  Article,  does  not  materially  differ  from 
the  corresponding  calculation  in  the  Theorie . . .des  Proh.;  97  is 
taken  as  the  number  of  comets  in  the  memoir,  and  100  in  the 
Theorie . . .  des  Proh. 

916.  Laplace  gives  an  investigation  the  object  of  which  is 
the  approximate  calculation  of  a  formula  which  occurs  in  the 
solution  of  the  problem  noticed  in  the  preceding  Article.  The 
formula  is  the  series  for  Zl'^s',  so  far  as  the  terms  consist  of 
positive  quantities  raised  to  the  power  which  i  denotes.  A  large 
part  of  the  memoir  bears  on  this  subject,  which  is  also  treated 
very  fully  in  the  Theorie... des  Proh.  pages  165 — 171,  475 — 482. 
This  memoir  contains  much  that  is  not  reproduced  in  the 
Theorie... des  Proh.,  being  in  fact  superseded  by  better  methods. 

We  may  remark  that  Laplace  gives  two  methods  for  finding  the 

value  of  I    fe~'^^''  cos  htdt,  but   he   does   not    notice   the  simplest 

''   0 

method,  which  would  be  to  differentiate       e-^^^  cos  htdt  four  times 

-J  0 

with  respect  to  h,  or  twice  with  respect  to  c ;  see  pages  368 — 370 
of  the  memoir. 

917.  In  pages  383 — 389  of  the  memoir  we  have  an  important 
investigation  resembling  that  given  in  pages  329 — 332  of  the 
TJieorie...des  Proh.,  which  amounts  to  finding  the  probability  that 
a  linear  function  of  a  large  number  of  errors  shall  have  a  certain 


LAPLACE.  489 

value,    the   law   of  facility   of  a   single    error   being   any  what- 
ever. 

Pages  390 — 397  of  the  memoir  are  spent  in  demonstrat- 
ing the  formula  marked  [q]  which  occurs  at  the  top  of  page  170 
of  the  Theorie...des  Prob.  The  remaining  pages  of  the  memoir 
amount  to  demonstrating  the  formula  marked  fp)  on  page  168  of 
the  Theor{e...des  Proh.,  which  is  again  discussed  in  pages  475 — 482 
of  the  Theorie...des  Prob.  The  methods  of  the  memoir  are  very 
laborious  and  inferior  to  those  of  the  Th^orie...des  Prob. 

918.  The  supplement  to  the  memoir  consists  of  the  matter 
Avhich  is  reproduced  in  pages  333 — 335  and  340 — 342  of  the 
TJieorie...des  Prob.  In  his  supplement  Laplace  refers  to  his 
memoir  of  1778;  see  Art.  901:  the  reference  is  not  preserved 
in  the  Theorie...des  Prob.  He  names  Daniel  Bernoulli,  Euler, 
and  Gauss;  in  the  corresponding  passage  on  page  335  of  the 
Theorie...des  Prob.,  he  simply  says,  des  geomUres  celebres. 

919.  Laplace's  next  memoir  is  entitled,  Me  moire  sur  les  Inte- 
grates  Definies,  et  leur  ajyj^Ucatiori  aux  Probabilites,  et  specialement 
a  la  recherche  dii  milieu  quil  faut  choisir  entre  les  residtats  des 
observations.  This  memoir  is  published  in  the  Memoires  ...de 
rinstitut  for  1810;  the  date  of  publication  is  1811  :  the  memoir 
occupies  pages  279 — 347  of  the  volume. 

920.  Laplace  refers  to  his  former  memoirs  on  Generating 
Functions  and  on  Approximations ;  he  speaks  of  the  approaching 
publication  of  his  work  on  Probabilities.  In  his  former  memoirs 
he  had  obtained  the  values  of  some  definite  integrals  by  the 
passage  from  real  to  imaginary  values ;  but  he  implies  that  such  a 
method  should  be  considered  one  of  invention  rather  than  of 
demonstration.  Laplace  says  that  Poisson  had  demonstrated  several 
of  these  results  in  the  Bidletiii  de  la  Societe  Philoinatique  for  March 
1811 ;  Laplace  now  proposes  to  give  direct  investigations. 

921.  The  first  investigation  is^that  which  is  reproduced  in 
pages  482 — 484  of  the  Theorie...des  Prob.  Then  follow  those 
which  are  reproduced  in  pages  97 — 99  of  the  Theorie...des  Prob. 
Next  we  have  the  problem  of  the  Duration  of  Play,  when  the 


490  LAPLACE. 

players  are  of  equal  skill  and  one  of  them  has  an  infinite  capital ; 
there  is  an  approximate  calculation  which  is  reproduced  in  pages 
235—238  of  the  Theorie...des  Proh.  Next  we  have  the  problem 
about  balls  and  the  long  dissertation  on  some  integrals  which  we 
find  reproduced  in  pages  287 — 298  of  the  Theorie...des  Proh. 
Lastly  we  have  the  theory  of  errors  substantially  coincident  with  so 
much  of  the  same  theory  as  we  find  in  pages  314 — 328  and 
340—342  of  the  Theorie...des  Proh. 

922.  A  theorem  may  be  taken  from  page  327  of  the  memoir, 
which  is  not  reproduced  in  the  Theorie...des  Proh. 

To  shew  that  if  ^|r  (x)  always  decreases  as  x  increases  between 
0  and  1  we  shall  have 

I  i/r  [x)  dx    greater   than    S  I  x'^^jr  (a?)  dx. 
Jo  •'o 

It  is  sufficient  to  shew  that 

x^  I   i/r  [x)  dx  is  greater  than  S  j   x^yjr  (x)  dx, 

or  that  2x  I   -v^^  (x)  dx  is  greater  than  2x^  -^  {x)y 


0 

r  X 


or  that  I   '^  (x)  dx  is  greater  than  x  -v/r  (x), 

"J  0 
1  ,     r     \     '  ,  i  1  I     /     \  d^  (x) 

or  that  Y  l*^)  ^^  greater  than  y  \F)  +  ^  — j —  ? 

but  this  is  obviously  true,  for     ^        is  negative. 

The  result  stated  on  page  321  of  the  Theorie...des  Proh.,  that 

k"  .  1     . 

under  a  certain  condition  -^  is  less  than  -  ,  is  an  example  of  this 

theorem. 

923.  In  the  Connaissance  des  Terns  for  1813,  which  is  dated 
July  1811,  there  is  an  article  by  Laplace  on  pages  213 — 223, 
entitled,  Du  milieu  qiiilfaut  choisir  entre  les  residtats  d'tin  grand 
nomhre  d'ohservations.  The  article  contains  the  matter  which  is 
reproduced  in  pages  322 — 329  of  the  Theorie...des  Proh.  Laplace 
speaks  of  his  work  as  soon  about  to  appear. 


LAPLACE.  491 

924.  In  the  Connaissance  des  Terns  for  1815,  which  is  dated 
November  1812,  there  is  an  article  on  pages  215 — 221  relating  to 
Laplace's  Theo7ne...des  Proh.  The  article  begins  with  an  extract 
from  the  work  itself,  containing  Laplace's  account  of  its  object 
and  contents.  After  this  follow  some  remarks  on  what  is  known 
as  Laplace's  nebular  hypothesis  respecting  the  formation  of  the 
solar  system.  Reference  is  made  to  the  inference  drawn  by  Michell 
from  the  group  of  the  Pleiades  ;  see  Art.  619. 

925.  In  the  Connaissance  des  Terns  for  1816,  which  is  dated 
November  1813,  there  is  an  article  by  Laplace,  on  pages  213 — 220, 
entitled,  Sur  les  Cometes. 

Out  of  a  hundred  comets  which  had  been  observed  not  one  had 
been  ascertained  to  move  in  an  hyperbola;  Laplace  proposes  to 
shew  by  the  Theory  of  Probability  that  this  result  might  have 
been  expected,  for  the  probability  is  very  great  that  a  comet  would 
move  either  in  an  ellipse  or  parabola  or  in  an  hyperbola  of  so 
great  a  transverse  axis  that  it  would  be  undistinguishable  from  a 
parabola. 

The  solution  of  the  problem  proposed  is  very  difficult,  from 
the  deficiency  of  verbal  explanation.     We  will  indicate  the  steps. 

Laplace  supposes  that  ?•  denotes  the  radius  of  the  sphere  of 
the  sun's  activity,  so  that  r  represents  a  very  great  length,  which 
may  be  a  hundred  thousand  times  as  large  as  the  radius  of  the 
earth's  orbit.  Let  V  denote  the  velocity  of  the  comet  at  the 
instant  wdien  it  enters  the  sphere  of  the  sun's  activity,  so  that  r 
is  the  comet's  radius  vector  at  that  instant.  Let  a  be  the  semi- 
axis  major  of  the  orbit  which  the  comet  proceeds  to  describe,  e 
its  excentricity,  D  its  perihelion  distance,  ■sr  the  angle  which  the 
direction  of  V  makes  with  the  radius  r.  Take  the  mass  of  the 
sun  for  the  unit  of  mass,  and  the  mean  distance  of  the  sun  from 
the  earth  as  the  unit  of  distance;  then  we  have  the  well-known 
formulse ; 

a     r 

r  V  sin  OT  =  Va  (1  —  e  ), 
I)  =  a{l-e). 


492  LAPLACE. 

From  these  equations  by  eliminating  a  and  e  we  have 


sin^  OT  = 


r 
7F 


and  from  this  we  deduce 


Now  if  we  suppose  that  when  the  comet  enters  the  sphere  of 
the  sun's  activity  all  directions  of  motion  which  tend  inwards 
are  equally  probable,  we  find  that  the  chance  that  the  direction 
will  make  an  angle  with  the  radius  vector  lying  between  zero 
and  OT  is  1  —  cos  'sr.  The  values  of  the  perihelion  distance  which 
correspond  to  these  limiting  directions  are  0  and  D.  Laplace 
then  proceeds  thus; 

...en  supposant  done  toutes  les  valeurs  de  D  egalement  possibles,  on 
a  pour  la  probabilite  que  la  distance  peiihelie  sera  comprise  entre  zero 
et  D, 


rV 


yf'^(-?)--} 


II  faut  multiplier  cette  valeur  par  dV ;  en  I'integrant  ensuite  dans 
des  limites  determinees,  et  divisant  I'integrale  j^ar  la  plus  grande  valeur 
de  V,  valeur  que  nous  designerons  par  U ;  on  aura  la  probabihte  que  la 
valeur  de  V  sera  comprise  dans  ces  limites.  Cela  pose,  la  plus  petite 
valeur  de  V  est  celle  qui  rend  nulle  la  quantite  renfermee  sous  le  radical 
precedent ;  ce  qui  donne 

J2I) 


rV  = 


A 


1.* 

r 


It  would  seem  that  the  above  extract  is  neither  clear  nor 
correct ;  not  clear  for  the  real  question  is  left  uncertain ;  not 
correct  in  what  relates  to  U.  We  will  proceed  in  the  ordinary  way, 
and  not  as  Laplace  does.     Let  'yjr  ( V)  stand  for 


rV 


.y/fp(l+f)-2Z)}; 


LAPLACE.  493 

then  we  have  found  that  supposing  all  directions  of  projection 
equally  probable,  if  a  comet  starts  with  the  velocity  V  the  chance 
is  >/r  ( F)  that  its  perihelion  distance  will  lie  between  0  and  D. 
Now  suppose  we  assume  as  a  fact  that  the  perihelion  distance 
does  lie  between  0  and  D,  but  that  we  do  not  know  the  initial 
velocity:  required  the  probability  that  such  initial  velocity  lies 
between  assigned  limits.  This  is  a  question  in  inverse  probability  ; 
and  the  answer  is  that  the  chance  is 


dV 


ff{V) 
fylr{V)dV 

where  the  integral  in  the  numerator  is  to  be  taken  between  the 
assigned  limits  ;  and  the  integral  in  the  denominator  between  the 
extreme  admissible  values  of  V. 

Laplace  finds  the  value  of    l'^{V)dV;   for  this  pmpose  he 

assumes 

For  the  assigned  limits  of  V  he  takes  ^  and  — 

The  value  of  \^|r{V)dV  between  these  limits  he  finds  to  be  ap- 
proximately 

2r  ir  sjr ' 

the  other  terms  involve  higher  powers  of  r  in  the  denominator, 
and  so  are  neglected. 

The  above  expression  is  the  numerator  of  the  chance  which 
we  require.  For  the  denominator  we  may  suppose  that  the  upper 
limit  of  the  velocity  is  infinite,  so  that  i  will  now  be  infinite. 
Hence  we  have  for  the  required  chance 

■{it -2)  si  IB  _    ^   \  ^  (tt  -  2)  V27> 
2r  ir^/r)    '  2r         ' 


494  LAPLACE, 

that  is, 


i  (tt  —  2)\lr' 

If  for  example  we  supposed  ^'  =  2,  we  should  have  the  extreme 
velocity  which  would  allow  the  orbit  to  be  an  ellipse. 

1      2 
In  the  equation  -  =  -—  V^  suppose  a  =  —  100  ;  then 

^^,     r  +  200     ,,         ..,     r  +  200 

^=T()or'  '^''''  ^=-100-- 

If  we  use  this  value  of  i  we  obtain  the  chance  that  the  orbit 
shall  be  either  an  ellipse  or  a  parabola  or  an  hyperbola  with 
transverse  axis  greater  than  a  hundred  times  the  radius  of  the 
earth's  orbit.  The  chance  that  the  orbit  is  an  hyperbola  with  a 
smaller  transverse  axis  will  be 

V2^ 

i  (tt  —  2)  ^r ' 

Laplace  obtains  this  result  by  his  process. 

Laplace  supposes  D  =  2,  r  =  100000  ;  and  the  value  of  i  to  be 
that  just  given:   he  finds  the  chance  to  be  about  v^^tt  • 

Laplace  then  says  that  his  analysis  supposes  that  all  values  of 
I)  between  0  and  2  are  equally  probable  for  such  comets  as  can 
be  perceived;  but  observation  shews  that  the  comets  for  which 
the  perihelion  distance  is  greater  than  1  are  far  less  numerous 
than  those  for  which  it  lies  between  0  and  1.  He  proceeds  to 
consider  how  this  will  modify  his  result. 

926.  In  the  Connaissance  des  Terns  for  1818,  which  is  dated 
1815,  there  are  two  articles  by  Laplace  on  pages  361 — 381 ;  the 
first  is  entitled,  Sur  VajypUcation  du  Calcid  des  Prohabilites  a  la 
Pkilosophie  naturelle;  the  second  is  entitled,  Sur  le  Calcul  des 
Prohabilites,  applique  a  la  Philosophie  naturelle.  The  matter  is 
reproduced  in  the  first  Supplement  to  the  Theorie...des  Proh. 
pages  1 — 25,  except  two  pages,  namely,  376,  377:  these  contain 
an  application  of  the  formulge  of  probability  to  determine  from 
observations  the  length  of  a  seconds'  pendulum. 


LAPLACE.  495 

927.  In  the  Connaissance  des  Terns  for  1820,  which  is  dated 
1818,  there  is  an  article  by  Laplace  on  pages  422 — 440,  entitled, 
Ajyplication  dii  Calcul  des  ProhahiUtes,  aux  ojje rations  geodesiqiies: 
it  is  reproduced  in  the  second  Supplement  to  the  Theorie...des 
Proh.  pages  1 — 25. 

928.  In  the  Connaissance  des  Terns  for  1822,  which  is  dated 
1820,  there  is  an  article  by  Laplace  on  pages  346 — 348,  entitled, 
Application  dii  Calcul  des  ProhahiUtes  aux  operations  geodesiqnes 
de  la  meridienne  de  France:  it  is  reproduced  in  the  third  Supple- 
ment to  the  Theorie . .  ,des  Proh.  pages  1 — 7. 

929.  We  have  now  to  speak  of  the  great  work  of  Laplace  which 
is  entitled,  Theorie  analytique  des  ProhahiUtes,  This  was  published 
in  1812,  in  quarto.  There  is  a  dedication  to  Napoleon-le-Grand  ; 
then  follow  445  pages  of  text,  and  afterwards  a  table  of  contents 
which  occupies  pages  446 — 464 :  on  another  page  a  few  errata 
are  noticed. 

The  second  edition  is  dated  1814,  and  the  third  edition  is 
dated  1820. 

The  second  edition  contains  an  introduction  of  cvi.  pages  ;  then 
the  text  paged  from  3  to  484  inclusive ;  then  a  table  of  contents 
which  occujiies  pages  485 — 506  :  then  two  pages  of  errata  are 
given. 

The  pages  9 — 444  of  the  first  edition  luere  not  reprinted  for 
the  second  or  third  edition  ;  a  few  pages  Avere  cancelled  and  re- 
placed, apparently  on  account  of  errata. 

The  third  edition  has  an  introduction  of  CXLII.  pages ;  and 
then  the  remainder  as  in  the  second  edition.  There  are,  however;, 
four  supplements  to  the  work  which  appeared  subsequently  to  the 
first  edition.  The  exact  dates  of  issue  of  these  supplements  do  not 
seem  to  be  given ;  but  the  first  and  second  supplements  were 
probably  published  between  1812  and  1820,  the  third  in  1820, 
and  the  fourth  after  1820.  Copies  of  the  third  edition  generally 
have  the  first  three  supplements,  but  not  the  fourth. 

930.  Since  the  bulk  of  the  text  of  Laplace's  work  ivas  not 
reprinted  for  the  editions  which  appeared  during  his  life  time. 


496  LAPLACE. 

a  reference  to  the  page  of  the  work  will  in  general  suffice  for 
any  of  these  editions  :  accordingly  we  shall  adopt  this  mode  of 
reference. 

An  edition  of  the  works  of  Laplace  was  published  in  France 
at  the  national  expense.  The  seventh  volume  consists  of  the 
Theorie...des  Proh.;  it  is  dated  1847.  This  volume  is  a  reprint  of 
the  third  edition.  The  title,  advertisement,  introduction,  and 
table  of  contents  occupy  cxcv.  pages ;  the  text  occupies  532 
pages,  and  the  four  supplements  occupy  pages  533 — 691. 

It  will  be  found  that  in  the  text  a  page  n  of  the  editions  pub- 

lished  by  Laplace  himself  will  correspond  nearly  to  the  page  ^  +  tt; 

of  the  national  edition :  thus  our  references  will  be  easily  available 
for  the  national  edition.  We  do  not  think  that  the  national 
edition  is  so  good  as  it  ought  to  have  been ;  we  found,  for  example, 
that  in  the  second  supplement  the  misprints  of  the  original  were 
generally  reproduced. 

931.  We  shall  now  proceed  to  analyse  the  work.  We  take  the 
third  edition,  and  we  shall  notice  the  places  in  which  the  introduc- 
tion differs  from  the  introduction  to  the  second  edition. 

The  dedication  was  not  continued  after  the  first  edition,  so  that 
it  may  be  interesting  to  reproduce  it  here. 

A  Napoleon-le-Grand.  Sire,  La  bienveillance  avec  laquelle  Yotre 
Majeste  a  daigne  accueillir  rhommage  de  mon  Traite  de  Mecanique 
Celeste,  m'a  inspire  le  desir  de  Lui  dedier  cet  Ouvrage  sur  le  Calcul  des 
Prohabilites.  Ce  calcul  delicat  s'etend  anx  questions  les  plus  impor- 
taiites  de  la  vie,  qui  ne  sout  en  effet,  pour  la  plupart,  que  des  j^roblemes 
de  probabilite.  11  doit,  sous  ce  rapport,  interesser  Yotre  Majeste  dont 
le  genie  sait  si  bien  apprecier  et  si  dignement  encourager  tout  ce  qui 
peut  contribuer  au  progres  des  lumieres,  et  de  la  prosperite  publique. 
J'ose  La  supplier  d'agreer  ce  nouvel  hommage  dicte  par  la  plus  vive 
reconnaissance,  et  par  les  sentimens  profonds  d'adiniration  et  de  respect, 
avec  lesquels  je  suis,  Sire,  de  Votre  Majeste,  Le  tres-liumble  et  tres- 
obeissant  serviteur  et  fidele  sujet,  Laplace. 

Laplace  has  been  censured  for  suppressing  this  dedication  after 
the  fall  of  Napoleon  ;  I  do  not  concur  in  this  censure.  The  dedi- 
cation appears  to  me  to  be  mere  adulation ;  and  it  would  have 


LAPLACE.  497 

been  almost  a  satire  to  have  repeated  it  when  the  tyrant  of  Europe 
had  become  the  mock  sovereign  of  Elba  or  the  exile  of  St  Helena  : 
the  fault  was  in  the  original  publication,  and  not  in  the  final  sup- 
pression. 

932.  We  have  said  that  some  pages  of  the  original  impression 
were  cancelled,  and  others  substituted ;  the  following  are  the  pages  : 
25,  26,  27,  28,  37,  38,  147,  148,  303,  304,  359,  360,  391,  392;  we 
note  them  because  a  student  of  the  first  edition  will  find  some 
embarrassing  errata  in  them. 

933.  The  introduction  to  the  Theorie...des  Proh.  was  pub- 
lished separately  in  octavo  under  the  title  of  Essai  pkilosophique 
sur  les  Prohahilites;  we  shall  however  refer  to  the  introduction 
by  the  pages  of  the  third  edition  of  the  Theorie...des  P7'ob. 

934.  On  pages  I — xvi.  of  the  introduction  we  have  some  gene- 
ral remarks  on  Probability,  and  a  statement  of  the  first  principles 
of  the  mathematical  theory ;  the  language  is  simple  and  the 
illustrations  are  clear,  but  there  is  hardly  enough  space  allotted  to 
the  subject  to  constitute  a  good  elementary  exposition  for  be- 
ginners. 

935.  On  pages  xvi — xxxvii.  we  have  a  section  entitled  Des 
mModes  analytiques  dii  Calcul  des  Probahilites ;  it  is  principally 
devoted  to  an  account  of  the  Theory  of  Generating  Functions,  the 
account  being  given  in  words  with  a  very  sparing  use  of  symbols. 
This  section  may  be  regarded  as  a  complete  waste  of  space ;  it 
would  not  be  intelligible  to  a  reader  unless  he  were  able  to  master 
the  mathematical  theory  delivered  in  its  appropriate  symbolical 
language,  and  in  that  case  the  section  would  be  entirely  super- 
fluous. 

This  section  differs  in  the  two  editions ;  Laplace  probably 
thought  he  improved  in  his  treatment  of  the  difficult  task  he  had 
undertaken,  namely  to  explain  abstruse  mathematical  processes  in 
ordinary  language.  We  will  notice  two  of  the  changes.  Laplace 
gives  on  pages  xxiiL  and  xxiv.  some  account  of  De  Moivre's 
treatment  of  Recurring  Series;  this  account  is  transferred  fi'om  page 
CI.  of  the  second  edition  of  the  introduction  :  a  student  however 

32 


498  LAPLACE. 

who  wished  to  understand  the  treatment  would  have  to  consult 
the  original  work,  namely  De  Moivre's  Miscellanea  Analytical 
pages  28 — 83.  Also  some  slight  historical  reference  to  Wallis  and 
others  is  introduced  on  pages  xxxv— xxxvn. ;  this  is  merely  an 
abridgement  of  the  pages  3 — 8  of  the  Theorie . . .des  Proh. 

936.  We  have  next  some  brief  remarks  on  games,  and  then 
some  reference  to  the  unknown  inequalities  which  may  exist  in 
chances  supposed  to  be  equal,  such  as  would  arise  from  a  want  of 
symmetry  in  a  coin  or  die ;  see  Arts.  877,  881,  891. 

937.  We  have  next  a  section  on  the  laws  of  probability,  which 
result  from  an  indefinite  multiplication  of  events ;  that  is  the 
section  is  devoted  to  the  consideration  of  James  Bernoulli's  theorem 
and  its  consequences.  Some  reflexions  here  seem  aimed  at  the 
fallen  emperor  to  whom  the  first  edition  of  the  work  was  dedicated  ; 
we  give  two  sentences  from  page  XLiii. 

Voyez  au  contraire,  dans  quel  abime  de  mallieurs,  les  peuples  ont 
ete  souvent  precipites  par  I'ambition  et  par  la  perfidie  de  leurs  chefs. 
Toutes  les  fois  qu'une  grande  puissance  enivree  de  I'amonr  des  conquetes, 
aspire  h  la  dominatiou  universelle;  le  sentiment  de  I'mdependance  pro- 
duit  entre  les  nations  menacees,  une  coalition  dont  elle  devient  presque 
toiijours  la  victinie. 

The  section  under  consideration  occurs  in  the  second  edition, 
but  it  occupies  a  different  position  there,  Laplace  having  made 
some  changes  in  the  arrangement  of  the  matter  in  the  third 
edition. 

We  may  notice  at  the  end  of  this  section  an  example  of  the 
absurdity  of  attempting  to  force  mathematical  expressions  into 
unmathematical  language.  Laplace  gives  a  description  of  a  certain 
probability  in  these  words  : 

La  theorie  des  fonctions  generatrices  donne  une  expression  tres 
simple  de  cette  probabilite,  que  Ton  obtient  en  integrant  le  produit  de 
la  differentielle  de  la  quantite  dont  le  resultat  deduit  d'un  grand  nombre 
d' observations  s'ecarte  de  la  verite,  par  une  coustante  moindre  que 
I'unite,  dependante  de  la  nature  du  probleriie,  et  elevee  a  une  puissance 
dont  I'exposant  est  le  rapport  du  carre  de  cet  ccart,  au  nombre  des 
observations.     L'integrale  prise  entre  des  limites   donnces,  et  divisee 


LAPLACE.  499 

par  la  meme  integrale  etendue  a  rinfini  positif  et  negatif,  exprimera  la 
probabilite  que  I'ecart  de  la  veiite,  est  compris  entre  ces  limites. 

A  student  familiar  with  the  Theorie...des  Proh.  itself  might 
not  find  it  easy  to  say  what  formula  Lajolace  has  in  view ;  it  must 
be  that  which  is  given  on  page  309  and  elsewhere,  namely 


dre  4A". 


7  " 

/J  TT 


Other  examples  of  the  same  absurdity  will  be  found  on  page  LL 
of  the  introduction,  and  on  page  5  of  the  first  supplement. 

938.  A  section  occupies  pages  XLix — LXX.  entitled  Applica' 
tion  du  Calcul  des  Probahilites,  d  la  Pliilosophie  naturelle.  Tbe 
principle  which  is  here  brought  forward  is  simple ;  we  will  take 
one  example  which  is  discussed  in  the  Theorie . .  .des  Prob.  If  a 
large  number  of  observations  be  taken  of  the  height  of  a  barometer 
at  nine  in  the  morning  and  at  four  in  the  afternoon,  it  is  found 
that  the  average  in  the  former  case  is  higher  than  in  the  latter ; 
are  we  to  ascribe  this  to  chance  or  to  a  constant  cause  ?  The 
theory  of  probabilities  shews  that  if  the  number  of  observations  be 
large  enough  the  existence  of  a  constant  cause  is  very  strongly  in- 
dicated. Laplace  intimates  that  in  this  way  he  had  been  induced 
to  undertake  some  of  his  researches  in  Physical  Astronomy,  be- 
cause the  theory  of  probabilities  shewed  irresistibly  that  there 
were  constant  causes  in  operation. 

Thus  the  section  contains  in  reality  a  short  summary  of  La- 
place's contributions  to  Physical  Astronomy ;  and  it  is  a  memor- 
able record  of  the  triumphs  of  mathematical  science  and  human 
genius.  The  list  comprises — the  explanation  of  the  irregularity 
in  the  motion  of  the  moon  arising  from  the  sj)heroidal  figure  of  the 
earth — the  secular  equation  of  the  moon — the  long  inequalities  of 
Jupiter  and  Saturn — the  laws  connecting  the  motions  of  the 
satellites  of  Jupiter — the  theory  of  the  tides.  See  Gouraud, 
page  115  ;  he  adds  to  the  list — the  tem23erature  of  the  earth  shewn 
'to  be  constant  for  two  thousand  years  :  it  does  not  appear  that 
Laplace  himself  here  notices  this  result. 

939.  Li    the    second    edition    of    the    Theorie  ...des    Proh. 

32—2 


500  LAPLACE. 

Laplace  did  not  include  the  secular  acceleration  of  the  moon  and 
the  theory  of  the  tides  in  the  list  of  his  labours  suggested  by  the 
Theory  of  Probability.  Also  pages  Li— LVL  of  the  introduction 
seem  to  have  been  introduced  into  the  third  edition,  and  taken 
from  the  first  supplement. 

Laplace  does  not  give  references  in  his  Theorie...des  Proh.,  so 
we  cannot  say  whether  he  published  all  the  calculations  respecting 
probability  which  he  intimates  that  he  made;  they  would  how- 
ever, we  may  presume,  be  of  the  same  kind  as  that  relating  to 
the  barometer  which  is  given  in  page  350  of  the  Theorie...desFroh., 
and  so  would  involve  no  novelty  of  principle. 

Laplace  alludes  on  page  Liv.  to  some  calculations  relating  to 
the  masses  of  Jupiter  and  Saturn;  the  calculations  are  given  in 
the  first  supplement.  Laplace  arrived  at  the  result  that  it  was 
1000000  to   1   that  the  error  in  the  estimation  of  the  mass  of 

Jupiter  could  not  exceed  —  of  the  whole  mass.     Nevertheless  it 

1 

has  since  been  recognised  that  the  error  was  as  large  as  —  ;   see 

Poisson,  Recherches sur  la  Proh...,  page  816. 

9-iO.  Laplace  devotes  a  page  to  the  Application  dii  Calcul 
des  Prohabilites  aux  Sciences  morales;  he  makes  here  some  inter- 
esting remarks  on  the  opposing  tendencies  to  change  and  to  con- 
servatism. 

9-tl.  The  next  section  is  entitled,  De  la  Prohahilite  des 
temoignages;  this  section  occupies  pages  Lxxi — Lxxxii :  it  is  an 
arithmetical  reproduction  of  some  of  the  algebraical  investigations 
of  Chapter  XL  of  the  Theorie...des  Proh.  One  of  Laplace's  discus- 
sions has  been  criticised  by  John  Stuart  Mill  in  his  Logic;  see 
Vol.  11.  page  172  of  the  fifth  edition.  The  subject  is  that  to  which 
we  have  alluded  in  Art.  735.  Laplace  makes  some  observations 
on  miracles,  and  notices  with  disapprobation  the  language  of 
Racine,  Pascal  and  Locke.  He  examines  with  some  detail  a 
famous  argument  by  Pascal  which  he  introduces  thus : 

Ici  se  presente  naturellement  la  discussion  d'un  argument  fameux 
de  Pascal,  que  Craig,  mathematicieii  anglais,  a  reproduit  sous  une  forme 


LAPLACE.  501 

geomtStriqiie.  Des  t^moiiis  attestent  qu'ils  tieunent  de  la  Divinite  meme, 
qu'en  se  conformant  k  telle  chose,  on  jouira,  non  pas  d'une  ou  de  deux, 
mais  d'une  infinite  de  vies  heureuses.  Quelque  faible  que  soit  la  proba- 
bilite  des  temoignages,  pourvu  quelle  ne  soit  pas  infiniment  petite;  11 
est  clair  que  I'avantage  de  ceux  qui  se  conforment  a  la  chose  prescrite, 
est  infini,  puisqu'il  est  le  produit  de  cette  probabilite  par  un  bien 
infiDi;  on  ne  doit  done  point  balancer  a  se  procurer  cet  avantage. 

See  also  the  Athenceum  for  Jan.  14tli,  1865,  page  oo. 

942.  The  next  section  is  entitled,  Des  clioix  et  des  decisions 
des  assemhUes;  it  occupies  four  pages:  results  are  stated  re- 
specting voting  on  subjects  and  for  candidates  which  are  obtained 
at  the  end  of  Chapter  ii.   of  the  Theorie...des  Proh. 

The  next  section  is  entitled,  De  la  probabilite  des  Jugemens 
des  tiibunaux;  it  occupies  five  pages:  results  are  stated  which 
are  obtained  in  the  first  supplement  to  the  Theo7'ie...des  Prob. 
This  section  is  nearly  all  new  in  the  third  edition  of  the 
Theorie. . .  des  Prob. 

The  next  section  is  entitled,  Des  Tables  de  mortalite,  et  des 
durees  moyennes  de  la  vie,  des  mariages  et  des  associations  quel- 
conques;  it  occupies  six  pages :  results  are  stated  which  are  ob- 
tained in  Chapter  VIIL  of  the  Theorie... des  Prob. 

The  next  section  is  entitled,  Des  benefices  des  etablissemens  qui 
dependent  de  la  probabilite  des  evenemens;  it  occupies  five  pages. 
This  section  relates  to  insurances :  results  are  given  which  are  ob- 
tained in  Chapter  ix.  of  the  Theorie... des  Prob. 

943.  The  next  section  is  entitled,  Des  illusions  dans  Vesti- 
mation  des  Probabilites ;  this  important  section  occupies  pages 
cii — cxxviii:  in  the  second  edition  of  the  Theorie... des  Prob.  the 
corresponding  section  occupied  little  more  than  seven  pages. 

The  illusions  which  Laplace  notices  are  of  various  kinds.  One 
of  the  principal  amounts  to  imagining  that  past  events  influence 
future  events  when  they  are  really  unconnected.  This  is  illus- 
trated from  the  example  of  lotteries,  and  by  some  remarks  on 
page  CIV.  relating  to  the  birth  of  a  son,  which  are  new  in  the 
third  edition.  Another  illusion  is  the  notion  of  a  kind  of  fatality 
which  gamblers  often  adopt. 

Laplace  considers  that   one   of  the  great  advantages  of  the 


502  LAPLACE. 

theory  of  probabilities  is  that  it  teaches  us  to  mistrust  our  first 
impressions;  this  is  ilkistratecl  by  the  example  which  we  have 
noticed  in  Art.  85G,  and  by  the  case  of  the  Chevaher  de  Mere: 
see  Art.  10.  Laplace  makes  on  his  page  cviii.  some  remarks  re- 
specting the  excess  of  the  births  of  boys  over  the  births  of  girls; 
these  remarks  are  new  in  the  third  edition. 

Laplace  places  in  the  list  of  illusions  an  application  of  the 
Theory  of  Probability  to  the  summation  of  series,  which  was 
made  by  Leibnitz  and  Daniel   BernoulK.     They   estimated   the 

infinite  series 

1-1+1-1  +  .. . 

as  equal  to  ^ ;  because  if  we  take  an  even  number  of  terms  we 

Jit 

obtain  0,  and  if  we  take  an  odd  number  of  terms  we  obtain  1, 
and  they  assumed  it  to  be  equally  probable  that  an  infinite 
number  of  terms  is  odd  or  even.  See  Dugald  Stewarfs  Works 
edited  hy  Hamilton,  Vol.  IV.  page  204. 

Laplace  makes  some  remarks  on  the  apparent  verification 
which  occasionally  happens  of  predictions  or  of  dreams;  and  justly 
remarks  that  persons  who  attach  importance  to  such  coincidences 
generally  lose  sight  of  the  number  of  cases  in  which  such  antici- 
pations of  the  future  are  falsified  by  the  event.     He  says, 

Ainsi,  le  pliilosophe  de  Tantiqiiite,  auqiiel  on  montrait  dans  un 
temple,  pour  exalter  la  puissance  du  dieu  qu'on  y  adorait,  les  ex  voto 
de  tons  cenx  qui  apres  I'avoir  invoqiie,  s'etaient  sauves  du  naufi^age,  fit 
une  remarque  conforme  au  calcul  des  prohabilites,  en  observant  qu'il 
ne  voyait  point  inscrits,  les  noms  de  ceux  qui,  malgre  cette  invocation, 
avaient  peri. 

944.  A  long  discussion  on  what  Laplace  calls  Psycliologie 
occupies  pages  cxiii — cxxviii  of  the  present  section.  There  is 
much  about  the  sensorium,  and  from  the  close  of  the  discussion  it 
would  appear  that  Laplace  fancied  all  mental  phenomena  ought 
to  be  explained  by  applying  the  laws  of  Dynamics  to  the  vibra- 
tions of  the  sensorium.  Indeed  we  are  told  on  page  cxxiv.  that 
faith  is  a  modification  of  the  sensorium,  and  an  extract  from 
Pascal  is  used  in  a  manner  that  its  author  would  scarcely  have 
approved. 


LAPLACE.  503 

94^5.  The  next  section  is  entitled,  Des  divers  moi/ens  d'ap- 
l^rocher  de  la  certitude;  it  occupies  six  pages.     Laplace  says, 

L'inductioii,  Tanalogie,  des  hypotheses  fondees  siir  les  faits  et  recti- 
fiees  sans  cesse  par  de  nouvelles  observations,  un  tact  heureux  donne 
par  la  nature  et  fortifie  par  des  comparaisons  nonibreuses  de  ses  indi- 
cations avec  I'experience;  tels  sont  les  priucipaux  moyens  de  parvenir 
a  la  verite. 

A  paragraph  beginning  on  page  cxxix.  with  the  words  Kous 
jugeons  is  new  in  the  third  edition,  and  so  are  the  last  four  lines 
of  page  cxxxii.  Laplace  cites  Bacon  as  having  made  a  strange 
abuse  of  induction  to  demonstrate  the  immobility  of  the  earth. 
Laplace  says  of  Bacon, 

II  a  donne  pour  la  recherche  de  la  verite,  le  precepte  et  non  I'ex- 
emple.  Mais  en  insistant  avec  toute  la  force  de  la  raison  et  de  I'elo- 
quence,  sur  la  necessite  d'abandonner  les  subtilites  insignifiantes  de 
I'ecole,  pour  se  livrer  aux  observations  et  aux  experiences,  et  en  indi- 
quant  la  vraie  niethode  de  s'elever  aux  causes  general es  des  phenomenes; 
ce  grand  philosophe  a  contribue  aux  progres  immenses  que  I'esprit 
humain  a  faits  dans  le  beau  siecle  ou  il  a  terniine  sa  carriere. 

Some  of  Laplace's  remarks  on  Analogy  are  quoted  with  ap- 
probation by  Dugald  Stewart;  see  his  Works  edited  hy  Hamilton^ 
Vol.  IV.  page  290. 

946.  The  last  section  of  the  introduction  is  entitled.  Notice 
historique  sur  le  Calcid  des  Prohabilites ;  this  is  brief  but  very 
good.  The  passage  extending  from  the  middle  of  page  cxxxix. 
to  the  end  of  page  CXLI.  is  new  in  the  third  edition;  it  relates 
principally  to  Laplace's  development  in  his  first  supplement  of 
his  theory  of  errors.  Laplace  closes  this  passage  with  a  reference 
to  the  humble  origin  of  the  subject  he  had  so  much  advanced;  he 
says  it  is  remarkable  that  a  science  which  began  with  the  consi- 
deration of  games  should  have  raised  itself  to  the  most  important 
objects  of  human  knowledge. 

A  brief  sketch  of  the  plan  of  the  Theorie...des  Proh.,  which 
appeared  on  the  last  page  of  the  introduction  in  the  second  edi- 
tion, is  not  repeated  in  the  third  edition. 

947.  The  words  in  which  at  the  end  of  the  introduction  La- 


50^  LAPLACE. 

place  sums  up  the  claims  of  the  Theory  of  Probability  well  deserve 
to  be  reproduced  here: 

On  voit  par  cet  Essai,  que  la  tlieorie  des  i^robaLilites  n'est  an  fond, 
que  le  bon  sens  reduit  au  calcul :  elle  fait  apprecier  avec  exactitude, 
ce  que  les  esprits  justes  sentent  par  une  sorte  d'instinct,  sans  qu'ils 
puissent  souvent  s'en  rendre  compte.  Si  Ton  considere  les  methodes 
analytiques  auxquelles  cette  theorie  a  donne  naissance,  la  verite  des 
principes  qui  lui  servent  de  base,  la  logique  fine  et  delicate  qu'exige 
leur  emploi  dans  la  solution  des  problemes,  les  etablissemens  d'utilite 
publique  qui  s'appuient  sur  elle,  et  I'extension  qu'elle  a  reque  et  qu'elle 
pent  recevoir  encore,  par  son  application  aux  questions  les  plus  impor- 
tantes  de  la  Philosophie  naturelle  et  des  sciences  morales;  si  Ton  ob- 
serve ensuite,  que  dans  les  clioses  memes  qui  ne  peuvent  etre  soumises 
au  calcul,  elle  donne  les  aperqus  les  plus  surs  qui  puissent  nous  guider 
dans  nos  jugemens,  et  qu'elle  apprend  a  se  garantir  des  illusions  qui 
souvent  nous  egarent;  on  verra  qu'il  n'est  point  de  science  plus  digne 
de  nos  meditations,  et  qu'il  soit  plus  utile  de  faire  entrer  dans  le  systeme 
de  r  instruction  publique. 

948.  We  now  leave  the  introduction  and  pass  to  the  Theorie... 
des  Proh.  itself  Laplace  divides  this  into  two  books.  Livre  I.  is 
entitled  Du  Calcul  des  Fonctions  Gene'ratrices:  this  occupies  pages 
1 — 177 ;  Livre  ii.  is  entitled  Theoi^e  generate  des  Prohahiliies; 
this  occupies  pages  179 — 461.  Then  follow  Additions  on  pages 
462—484. 

949.  The  title  which  Laplace  gives  to  his  Livre  I.  does  not 
adequately  indicate  its  contents.  The  subject  of  generating  func- 
tions, strictly  so  called,  forms  only  the  first  part  of  the  book  ;  the 
second  part  is  devoted  to  the  consideration  of  the  approximate 
calculation  of  various  expressions  which  occur  in  the  Theory  of 
Probability. 

950.  The  first  part  of  Livre  i.  is  almost  a  reprint  of  the  me- 
moir of  1779  in  which  it  originally  appeared ;  see  Art.  906.  This 
part  begins  with  a  few  introductory  remarks  on  pages  3 — 8  ;  these 
pages  3 — 8  of  the  third  edition  do  not  quite  agree  with  the  pages 
1 — 8  of  the  first  edition,  but  there  is  nothing  of  consequence  pecu- 
liar to  the  first  edition.  Laplace  draws  attention  to  the  importance 
of  notation  in  mathematics;  and  he  illustrates  the  point  by  the 


LAPLACE.  505 

advantage  of  the  notation  for  denoting  powers,  which  leads  him 
to  speak  of  Descartes  and  Wallis. 

Laplace  points  out  that  Leibnitz  made  a  remarkable  use  of  the 
notation  of  powers  as  applied  to  differentials ;  this  use  we  might 
describe  in  modern  terms  as  an  example  of  the  separation  of  the 
symbols  of  operation  and  quantity.  Lagrange  followed  up  this 
analogy  of  powers  and  differentials ;  his  memoir  inserted  in  the 
volume  for  1772  of  the  memoirs  of  the  Academy  of  Berlin  is  cha- 
racterised by  Laplace  as  one  of  the  finest  applications  ever  made  of 
the  method  of  inductions. 

951.  The  first  Chapter  of  the  first  part  oi  Livre  I.  is  entitled 
Des  Fonctions  generati^ices,  ct  une  variable;  it  occupies  pages  9 — 49. 

The  method  of  generating  functions  has  lost  much  of  its  value 
since  the  cultivation  of  the  Calculus  of  Operations  by  Professor 
Boole  and  others ;  partly  on  this  account,  and  partly  because  the 
method  is  sufficiently  illustrated  in  works  on  the  Theory  of  Finite 
Differences,  we  shall  not  explain  it  here. 

Pasres  39 — 49  contain  various  formulae  of  what  we  now  call  the 
Calculus  of  Operations ;  these  formulse  cannot  be  said  to  be  cle- 
monstrated  by  Laplace ;  he  is  content  to  rely  mainly  on  analogy. 
LagTange  had  led  the  way  here  ;  see  the  preceding  Article. 

One  of  the  formulae  may  be  reproduced ;  see  Laplace's  page  41. 
If  we  write  Taylor's  theorem  symbolically  we  obtain 


Ay.=  v/^^-Vj/., 


where  A  indicates  the  difference  in  y^  arising  from  a  difference  h  in 
X.     Then 

Laplace  transforms  this  into  the  following  result, 


2 


/  hd_ 

The  following  is  his  method : 

/d_  Y  nh£/  hd_  h  dY 

W^"^  -l)y.  =  e  ^.^'^•^  Ve2  ci^  _  ^'2  dx)  y^^ 


506  LAPLACE. 


Now  let  ^  ( -7-  j  denote  any  term  arising  from  the  development  of 


I  g2  dx Q~  2dxj 

Then  ,(^)....^^=,(^),,, 


and  the  term  on  the  right  hand  may  be  supposed  to  have  arisen 


/  hd_      _IlAY 
Ve2  dx_ 


from  the  development  of  \e^  ^^^  —  e    ^  ^^J  y^^'^-    Thus  the  formula 

2 
is  considered  to  be  established. 

We  ought  to  observe  that  Laplace  does  not  express  the  formula 
quite  in  the  way  which  we  adopt.  His  mode  of  writing  Taylor's 
Theorem  is 

and  then  he  would  write 

Ay,=\e  "-  -1). 

He  gives  verbal  directions  as  to  the  way  in  which  the  symbols 
are  to  be  treated,  which  of  course  make  his  formulae  really  iden- 
tical with  those  which  we  express  somewhat  differently.  We  may 
notice  that  Laplace  uses  c  for  the  base  of  the  Napierian  logarithms, 
which  we  denote  by  e. 

If  in  the  formula  we  put  h  =  l  and  change  x  into  a?  —  -  we 

obtain 

/  1  £,  1  d\' 

2 

which  Laplace  obtains  on  his  page  45  by  another  process. 

952.  The  second  Chapter  of  the  first  part  of  Livre  L  is  entitled 
Des  fonctions  generatrices  a  deux  variables:  it  occupies  pages 
50—87. 

Laplace  applies  the  theory  of  generating  functions  to  solve 
equations  in  Finite  Differences  with  two  independent  variables. 
He  gives  on  his  pages  63 — (j^>  a  strange  process  for  integrating  the 
following  equation  in  Finite  Differences, 


LAPLACE.  507 

We  might  suppose  that  z^,^  is  the  coefficient  of  fr'  in  the  ex- 
pansion of  a  function  of  t  and  r ;  then  it  would  easily  follow  that 
this  function  must  be  of  the  form 

^[t)^'^  (t) 
nab       \' 

Tti C 

\Tt        T        t  J 

where  </>  (t)  is  an  arbitrary  function  of  t,  and  yjr  (r)  an  arbitrary 
function  of  r. 

Laplace,  however,  proceeds  thus.     He  puts 

1      a     h  ^ 
-c  =  0, 

Tt        T        t 

and  he  calls  this  the  equation  generatrice  of  the  given  equation  in 
Finite  Differences.  He  takes  u  to  denote  the  function  of  t  and  t 
which  when  expanded  in  powers  of  t  and  r  has  z^,  y  for  the  co- 

u 

efficient  of  fi^.      Then  in  the  expansion  of  -^-^  the  coefficient  of 

^V^willbe^,,,. 

Laplace  then  transforms  —^  thus.  By  the  equation  generatrice 
we  have 

1  T 


'     i-6 

T 


therefore, 


u  \T      h      h) 


c  +  ah  +  a  f h 


(I  _  ,)^ 

Develope  the  second  member  according  to  powers  of 5 ; 


thus 

u 

f~r 


,-'l(H'-''M"-'-^'-M"-^-] 


,ar-2 


,   _     X  (c  +  ah)  a""'^     x(x  —  l),    ,     ,,2     ^' 
X  l^'+-^"J +      1.2      (^  +  ^^)  7l ^ 


T  Vt  y 


508  LAPLACE. 

Multiply  the  two  series  together.     Let 

Fj  =  yld'  +  a;  (c  +  al)  a"'^, 

J-  ■  ^  1 .  ^ 

Tr_y(y-i)Cy-2)„  . 


Then 


^^=4^f--^y+F.f--^rv...-^^. 


.T  /  VT 


T  \T  J  \T  J 


But  the  equation 


gives 


1      «j     5 

7 --c  =  0 

CT        T         C 


1 

1      ,      c  +  a6  ' 
0 

T 


therefore 


Now  we  pass  from  the  generating  functions  to  the  coefficients, 
and  we  pick  out  the  coefficients  of  ^V°  on  both  sides.  This  gives 
z^y  on  the  left-hand  side,  and  on  the  right-hand  side  a  series 
which  we  shall  now  proceed  to  express. 

Let  A  apply  to  x,  and  indicate  a  Finite  Difference  produced 
by  the  change  of  x  into  ic  +  1  ;  and  let  8  similarly  apply  to  ?/,  and 
indicate  a  Finite  Difference  produced  by  the  change  of  7/  into 
2/+1. 


LAPLACE.  509 

Now  [ ^]  ^^[1 ■"-)  J  hence  in  u( h)    the  coefficient 

of  fr^  will  be  h't''  (-jiA  >  provided  we  suppose  that  ?/  is  made  zero 
after  the  operation  denoted  by  8''  has  been  performed  on  -^ . 

Similarly  in  w  (^  -  aj  the  coefficient  of  fr'  wiU  be  oTA'  (^/] , 
provided  we  suppose  that  x  is  made  zero  after  the  operation  de- 
noted  by  A'"  has  been  performed  on  -^ . 

In  this  way  we  obtain 

+     ^     V    A  (^]  +  — ^  F    A'^  (^] 


IT  K  f    (     X    A 

+  •  •  •  +  7 : 7T-  r  y^y.  A     I  — ^ 


Thus  we  see  that  in  order  to  obtain  z^^y  we  must  know 
^0, 1  >  ^0, 2' •  •  •  ^P  ^^  ^0,  V >  ^nd  we  must  know  z^^^,  ^2,  c  •  •  ^p  to  z^^  „ . 

Now  we  have  to  observe  that  this  process  as  given  by  Laplace 
cannot  be  said  to  be  demonstrative  or  even  intelligible.  His 
method  of  connecting  the  two  independent  variables  by  the  equation 
generatrice  without  explanation  is  most  strange. 

But  the  student  who  is  acquainted  with  the  modern  methods 
of  the  Calculus  of  Operations  will  be  able  to  translate  Laplace's 
process  into  a  more  familiar  language. 

Let  E  denote  the  change  of  x  into  x  +  1,  and  F  the  change  of 

7/  into  ?/  +  1 :  then  the  fundamental  equation  we  have  to  integrate 

will  be  written 

{EF- aF-  bE-  c)  z,^,  =  0, 

or  for  abbreviation 

EF-aF-bE-c  =  0, 

Then  E'^F^  will  be  expanded  in  the   way  Laplace   expands 
and  his  result  obtained  from  E^'F^z^^^.     Thus  we  rely  on  the 


foundations  on  which  the  Calculus  of  Operations  is  based. 


510  LAPLACE. 

We  may  notice  tliat  we  have  changed  Laplace's  notation  in 
order  to  avoid  the  dashes  which  are  difficult  in  printing.  La- 
place uses  X  where  we  use  y,  t!  where  we  use  r,  and  'A  where  we 
use  8. 

953.  Laplace  takes  another  equation  in  Finite  Differences. 
The  equation  we  will  denote  thus 

A"^,„+^A»-a^,.,+ J  A-^ax,  + ...  =  0. 

Here  A  belongs  to  x  of  which  the  difference  is  unity;  and  S 
belongs  to  y  of  which  the  difference  is  a. 

Laplace  says  that  the  equation  generatrice  is 

e-r*K'-r(i-)4.&-r&-r--=»- 

He  supposes  that  this  equation  is  solved,  and  thus  decomposed 
into  the  following  n  equations  : 

t  a\        W 

t  a  V        TV ' 


where  q,  q^,  q^}"*  ^^^  the  n  roots  of  the  equation 
Then,  using  the  first  root 


u 


u         u  f^       q 

^'    x.r'u. 

<i\   1 

Then  passing  from  the  generating  functions  to  the  coefficients, 
that  is  equating  the  coefficients  of  ^V°,  we  obtain 


LAPLACE.  511 


The  second  member  may  be  put  in  tlie  form 


0 


Denote  the  quantity  [ — —Vz^^y  by  the  arbitrary  function 
</)  (?/).     Thus 

This  value  of  Zx,y  will  then  satisfy  the  equation  in  Finite  Dif- 
ferences. 

Each  of  the  n  roots  q,  q^,  q^,  ...  gives  rise  to  a  similar  ex- 
pression ;  and  the  sum  of  the  7i  particular  values  thus  obtained  for 
Zx  y  will  furnish  the  general  value,  involving  n  arbitrary  functions. 

The  student  will  as  before  be  able  to  translate  this  process 
into  the  language  of  the  Calculus  of  Operations. 

Laplace  continues  thus  :  Suppose  a  indefinitely  small,  and 
equal  to  dy.     Then 

as  we  may  see  by  taking  logarithms.     Thus  we  shall  obtain 

This  is  the  complete  integral  of  the  equation 

Laplace  next  gives  some  formulae  of  what  we  now  call  the  Cal- 
culus of  Operations,  in  the  case  of  two  independent  variables  ;  see 
his  pages  68 — 70. 

954.  In  his  pages  70 — 80  Laplace  offers  some  remarks  on  the 
transition  from  the  finite  to  the  indefinitely  small ;  his  object  is  to 
shew  that  the  process  will  furnish  rigorous  demonstrations.  He 
illustrates  by  referring  to  the  problem  of  vibrating  strings,  and 
this  leads  him  to  notice  a  famous  question,  namely  that  of  the  ad- 
missibility of  discontinuous  functions  in  the  solution  of  partial  dif- 


512  LAPLACE. 

ferential  equations;  he  concludes  that  such  functions  are  ad- 
missible under  certain  conditions.  Professor  Boole  reofards  the 
argument  as  unsound ;  see  his  Finite  Differences,  Chapter  x. 

955.  Laplace  closes  the  Chapter  with  some  general  considera- 
tions respecting  generating  functions.  The  only  point  to  which  we 
need  draw  attention  is  that  there  is  an  important  error  in  page  82 ; 
Laplace  gives  an  incomplete  form  as  the  solution  of  an  equation  in 
Finite  Differences ;  the  complete  form  will  be  found  on  page  5  of 
the  fourth  supplement.  We  shall  see  the  influence  of  the  error 
hereafter  in  Arts.  974,  980,  984. 

956.  We  now  arrive  at  the  second  part  of  Livre  i.,  this  is 
nearly  a  reprint  of  the  memoir  for  1782;  the  method  of  approxi- 
mation had  however  been  already  given  in  the  memoir  for  1778. 
See  Arts.  894,  899,  907,  921. 

The  first  chapter  of  the  second  part  of  Livre  I.  is  entitled  Be 
Tintegixttion  jjar  approximation,  des  differe^itielles  qui  renferment 
des  facteurs  Sieves  a  de  grandes  puissances;  this  Chapter  occupies 
pages  88—109. 

957.  The  method  of  approximation  which  Laplace  gives  is  of 
great  value  :  we  will  explain  it.     Suppose  we  require  the  value  of 

\ydx  taken  between  two  values  of  x  which  include  a  value  for 

which  y  is  a  maximum.     Assume  y  —  Fe-^^,  where  F  denotes  this 
maximum  value  of  y.     Then 

jydx=YJe-<^^dt. 

Let  y  =  (j)  {x)  ;  suppose  a  the  value  of  x  which  makes  y  have 
the  value  Y :  assume  x=  a+  6. 

Thus  (^(a  +  (9)=  Ye-''; 

Y 

therefore  f  =  log  -7-7 ^r  . 

(p  {a-^  o) 

From  this  equation  we  may  expand  ^  in  a  series  of  ascending 
powers  of  6,  and  then  by  reversion  of  series  we  may  obtain  6  in  a 
series  of  ascending  powers  of  t.     Suppose  that  thus  we  have 


LAPLACE.  513 

then  J  =  J  =  ^,  +  2i?,^  +  353^+...; 

[ydx  =  YJe-^'  {B^  +  2B,t  +  SBf  +  ...)  dt. 

Such  is  the  method  of  Laplace.  It  will  be  practically  advan- 
tageous in  the  cases  where  B^,  B^,  B^,  ...  form  a  rapidly  converging 
series;  and  it  is  to  such  cases  that  we  shall  have  to  apply  it,  when 
we  give  some  examples  of  it  from  Laplace's  next  Chapter.  In 
these  examples  there  will  be  no  difficulty  in  calculating  the  terms 
B^,  B^,  B^,  ...,  so  far  as  we  shall  require  them.  An  investigation  of 
the  general  values  of  these  coefficients  as  far  as  B^  inclusive  will  be 
found  in  De  Morgan's  Differential  and  hitegral  Calculus,  page  602. 

If  we  suppose  that  the  limits  of  x  are  such  as  to  make  the  cor- 
responding values  of  y  zero,  the  limits  of  t  will  be  —  co  and  +  oo  . 

Now  if  r  be  odd  I     e-^'fdt  vanishes,  and  if  r  be  even  it  is  equal  to 

^   —00 

(^_1)(^_3)...  3.1 
Thus  we  have 


i^ 


3  5   3 

ydx=  Ys/ir\B^-]r-^B^-^-i^  B^-^.,.\. 


Besides  the  transformation  y  =  Ye~^^  Laplace  also  takes  cases 
in  which  the  exponent  of  e  instead  of  being  —  f  has  other  values. 
Thus  on  his  page  88  the  exponent  is  —  t,  and  on  his  page  93 
it  is  —  f'' ;  in  the  first  of  these  cases  Y  is  not  supposed  to  be  a 
maximum  value  of  y. 

958.  Some  definite  integrals  are  given  on  pages  95 — 101,  in 
connexion  with  which  it  may  be  useful  to  supply  a  few  references. 

The  formula  marked  {T)  on  page  95  occurs  in  Laplace's  memoir 
of  1782,  page  17. 

COS  rx  e**  ^  dx  =  -^r-  e   ia" . 

Jo  2« 

this   was  given  by  Laplace  in   the  Memoires...de   llnstitut    for 
1810,  page  290 ;  see  also  Tables  dlntegrales  Definies,  1858,  by 

D.  Bierens  de  Haan,  page  376. 

S3 


514  LAPLACE. 


/, 


dx-=^  ^ 

0  ^  ^ 


see  D.  Bierens  de  Haan,  page  268. 

where  a  is  supposed  positive ;  these  seem  due  to  Laplace  ;  see 
D.  Bierens  de  Haan,  page  282,  TMorie...desProh.,  pages  99—134. 
We  may  remark  that  these  two  results,  together  with 


/■ 

J  0 


sin  ax  dx     it  ,^  „•. 

1  -i-  X     X  Z 


are  referred  by  D.  F.  Gregory,  in  his  Examples  ofthe.,.Diffe7'ential 
and  Integral  Calcidus,  to  Laplace's  memoir  of  1782 ;  but  they  are 
not  explicitly  given  there :  with  respect  to  the  last  result  see 
D.  Bierens  de  Haan,  page  293. 

959.     Since  the  integral   le~^'  dt  occurs  in  the  expressions  of 

Art.  957,  Laplace  is  led  to  make  some  observations  on  modes  of 
approximating  to  the  value  of  this  integral.  He  gives  the  follow- 
ing series  which  present  no  difficulty : 


/, 


t'      1  t'      1  t' 
e-'V<  =  T-3+^g-^^  +  ...; 


j;>.,.„,-..(..K.jiS!.,5^*...)> 

In  the  memoir  of  1782  the  second  of  these  three  expressions 
does  not  occur. 

Laplace  also  gives  a  development  of  I     e'^"^  dt  into  the  form  of 

J  T 

a  continued  fraction,  which  he  takes  from  his  MScanique  Celeste, 
Livy^e  x.  See  also  De  Morgan's  Differential  and  Integral  Calculus, 
page  591,  for  this  and  some  similar  developments. 


LAPLACE.  515 

9 GO.  Laplace  extends  the  method  of  approximation  given  in 
Art.  957  to  the  case  of  double  integrals.  The  following  is  substan- 
tially his  process.     Suppose  we  require   \\ydxdx'  taken  between 

such  limits  of  x  and  x  as  make  y  vanish.  Let  Y  denote  the 
maximum  value  of  y,  and  suppose  that  a  and  a  are  the  correspond- 
ing values  of  x  and  x.     Assume  , 

y=Ye-''-^\ 

X  =  a  +  6,  x  =  a  -\-  6'. 

Y 

Substitute  these  values  of  x  and  x   in  the  function  log  —  and 

expand  it  in  powers  of  6  and  6' ;  then  since  Y  is  by  hypothesis  the 
maximum  value  of  y  the  coefficients  of  6  and  6'  will  vanish  in  this 
expansion :  hence  we  may  write  the  result  thus 

that  is  J/  ("  (9  +  ^  ^'V  j^(p-^\  d"  =e^  t'\ 

Since  we  have  made  only  one  assumption  respecting  the  inde- 
pendent variables  t  and  t'  w^e  are  at  liberty  to  make  another  ;  we 
will  assume 

and  therefore  6'     /(p-^\^t'. 

Now  by  the  ordinary  theory  for  the  transformation  of  double 
integrals  we  have 

\ydxdx  =  jj  ^ , 

,  T-K    ,       1     r  dt  dt'       dt  dt' 

where  x>  stands  lor         -7-,  ^7^,  — -,^,  -77: . 

du  do      do  do 

Thus  far  the  process  is  exact.  For  an  approximation  we  may 
suppose  M,  N,  P  to  be  functions  of  a  and  a  only ;  then  we  have 

2r   da"  '  tY  dada"  2Y  da"' 


O 


3—2 


516  LAPLACE. 

Then  we  sliall  find  that 


n       //DiT     A72N        1       /{d'^Yd'Y      fd'Y\\ 

And  the  limits  of  t  and  t'  will  be  —  (X)  and  +  co  ;  thus  finally 
we  have  approximately 


I  \y  dx  dx  — 


/{d'Y  d'Y 
y  \dd'    da!' 


2irY^ 

(  d'Y 


jda  da  I 
See  Art.  907. 

961.  The  second  Chapter  of  the  second  part  of  Livre  l.  is 
entitled  De  ^integration  par  approximation,  des  Equations  lineaires 
aux  differences  finies  et  infiniment  petites :  this  Chapter  occupies 
pages  110 — 125. 

This  Chapter  exemplifies  the  process  of  solving  linear  differential 
equations  by  the  aid  of  definite  integrals.  Laplace  seems  to  be 
the  first  who  drew  attention  to  this  subject :  it  is  now  fully  dis- 
cussed in  works  on  differential  equations.  See  Boole's  Differential 
Equations. 

962.  The  third  Chapter  of  the  second  part  of  Livre  L  is 
entitled  App)lication  des  m^thodes  prdc^dentes,  a  V ap>proximation 
de  diverses  fonctions  de  tres-grands  nonibi^es:  this  Chapter  oc- 
cupies pages  126 — 177. 

The  first  example  is  the  following.  Suppose  we  have  to  in- 
tegrate the  equation  in  Finite  Differences, 

Assume  y^—  ix'ipdx,  where  ^  is  a  function  of  x  at  present 

undetermined,   and  the  limits  of  the  integration  are  also  unde- 
termined. 

Let  By  stand  for  x" ;  then  -~^  =  sx^~'^.     Hence  the  proposed 


equation  becomes 


LAPLACE,  0I7 

that  is,  by  integrating  by  parts, 

0  =  [xhy<f>]  +j  |(1  -^)  ^-^  (#)j  Bi/dx. 

Wliere  by  [xBi/^]  we  mean  that  xhy^  is  to  be  taken  between 
limits. 

Assume  </>  such  that 

and  take  the  limits  of  integration  such  that  [^  %  </>]  =  0 ;  then 
our  proposed  equation  is  satisfied. 

From  (1  —  cc)  (^  — y-  (x(^)  =  0,  we  obtain 

where  ^  is  a  constant.     Then  xBi/ (f>  will  vanish  when  x=  0  and 
also  when  cc  =  00 .     Thus,  finally 


/•CO" 


x^e'^dx. 

Now  we  proceed  to  put  this  integral  in  the  form  of  a  series. 
The  maximum  value  of  ic*e~*  is  easily  found  to  be  that  which 
corresponds  to  a;  =  5.     Assume,  according  to  Art.  957, 

23*  e"*  =  s'e~^e~^\ 


8. 


and  put  x—s-\-Q\  thus 

Take  the  logarithms  of  both  sides ;  thus 

Hence  by  reversion  of  series  we  get 

3         9  V2s 


518  LAPLACE. 


therefore  dx^dQ^  di  V25  1 1  +  — r—  +  -^ 

\        3V25      65 

The  limits  of  t  corresponding  to  the  limits  0  and  go  of  a;  will 
be  —  00  and  +  00  .     Therefore 

/-«>  /"»  (  ^t         ^  \ 

Jo  J -00  I        8V2s      65  J 

By  integration  we  obtain 


y. 


==As'^^e-'\^'27r  \l+  Y^+  ...\  . 


Laplace  says  we  may  determine  the  value  of  the  factor 

very  simply  thus. 

7?      O 

Denote  it  by  1  ■] H -7  +  ...  so  that 

•^  s      s 

7/,  =  As'^'^e-W2^h  +  j  +  ~  +  ...\ 
Substitute  this  value  in  the  equation 


thus 


'       ly^^  _,  r        B  C  ]     ,      B     0  , 


therefore 


n.?+f+...){;-H)-('n)_^} 


8         S 


B     B-2G 

--^  +  — ^j— +  ... 

And 

~      126'^  "^12s^^      ••' 
Thus 

f,      B     G         \  (       1  1  I         ^  ,  B-20 


s   '  ^^  '       J        12s'  '  12/  s'  '       s 


3 


LAPLACE.  519 


Hence,  equating  coefficients, 

^  ~  12  '  288  ' 


The  value  of  A  in  the  expression  for  y^  must  be  determined 
by  some  particular  value  of  ?/g.  Suppose  that  when  s  =  yx  we 
have  2/^=  Y. 

Then  Y^A\    x^e'^dx^ 

J  a 


thus  A  = 


0 

Y 


/•OO 

Hence 

Vs-    p  i^+ 12s'^288/"^*"'i* 

I    x^  e    ax 

^  0 

The  original  equation  can  be  very  easily  integrated;  and  we 

obtain 

y,^  rOL6  +  l)0+2)  ...5. 

Hence,  by  equating  the  two  values  of  y^, 
(/i  +  1)  (/I +2)  ...s  = 


•^  0 


a;'^  e"'"  cfa? 


It  will  be  observed  that  5  —  /z  is   assumed  to  be  a  positive 
integer,  but  there  is  nothing  to  require  that  5  itself  should  be  an 


integer. 


963.    One  remark  must  be  made  on  the  process  which  we  have 
just  given.     Let  0  (s)  denote 


*■  "T    T(r>_'ooo^2'" 


will  be  denoted  by  <f>{—s). 

Now  Laplace  does  not  shew  that 


520  LAPLACE. 

although  he  assumes  the  truth  of  this  on  his  page  134).  It  may 
be  shewn  by  adopting  the  usual  mode  of  proving  Stirling's  Theo- 
rem. For  by  using  Euler's  theorem  for  summation,  given  in 
Art.  334,  it  will  appear  that 

where  t  (^)  =  9^  "  ^l73  +       ' 


26^      3.4/  '  5.Qs'  ' 

the  coefficients  being  the  well-known  numhers  of  Bernoidli. 

Thus  'i/r(5)+i/r(-5)=0; 

therefore  e^^'^  x  e^^"^  =  e' ^1, 

that  is  </)  (5)  <^  (—  5)  =  1. 

964.  Laplace,  after  investigating  a  formula  sometimes  de- 
duces another  from  it  by  passing  from  real  to  imaginary  quantities. 
This  method  cannot  be  considered  demonstrative ;  and  indeed 
Laplace  himself  admits  that  it  may  be  employed  to  discover  new 
formulae,  but  that  the  results  thus  obtained  should  be  confirmed 
by  direct  demonstration.     See  his  pages  87  and  471;  also  Art.  920. 

Thus  as  a  specimen  of  his  results  we  may  quote  one  which  he 
gives  on  his  page  134. 


Let  Q  =  cos  CT 


(^^ + ^r 


then 


/<00 


('00  • 

J  0 


A  memoir  by  Cauchy  on  Definite  Integrals  is  published  in  the 
Journal  de  VEcole  Folytechnique,  28^  Cahier ;  this  memoir  was 
presented  to  the  Academy  of  Sciences,  Jan.  2nd,  1815,  but  not 
printed  until  1841.  The  memoir  discusses  very  fully  the  results 
given  by  Laplace  in  the  Chapter  we  are  now  considering.  Cauchy 
says,  page  148, 

...je   suis  parvenu  a  qiielques  resultats    nouveaux,   ainsi  qii'a   la 
demonstration  directe  de  plusieurs  formules,  que  M.  Laplace  a  deduites 


LAPLACE.  521 

du  passage  du  r^el  a  rimaginaire,  dans  le  3"^®  chapitre  du  Calcul  d'^s 
P^'ohahilites,  et  qu'il  vient  de  confirmer  par  des  metliodes  rigoureuses 
dans  quelques  additions  faites  a  cet  ouvrage. 

The  additions  to  which  Cauchy  refers  occupy  pages  464 — 484 
of  the  Theorie...des  Froh.,  and  first  appeared  in  the  second  edi- 
tion, which  is  dated  1814. 

965.  An  important  application  which  Laplace  makes  of  his 
method  of  approximation  is  to  evaluate  the  coefficients  of  the 
terms  in  the  expansion  of  a  high  power  of  a  certain  polynomial. 

Let  the  polynomial  consist  of  2n  +  l  terms  and  be  denoted 
by 

111  1 

-^  +  -iFT  +  -1F2  +  —  +  -  + 1  +  «+•••  +  «""'  +  «*""'  +  «" ; 

a       a         a   ^  a 

and  suppose  the  polynomial  raised  to  the  power  s. 

First,  let  it  be  required  to  find  the  coefficient  of  the  term 
independent  of  a. 

Substitute  e^^^^  for  a ;  then  we  require  the  term  which  is 
independent  of  6  when 


{ 


l  +  2cos^  +  2cos2^+  ...  +  2cos?i^y 


is  expanded  and  arranged  according  to  cosines  of  multiples  of  0. 
This  term  will  be  found  by  integrating  the  above  expression  with 
respect  to  6  from  0  to  tt,  and  dividing  by  tt.  Sum  the  series  of 
cosines  by  the  usual  formula ;  then  the  required  term 


.    2w  +  l^ 
t    n^  1  sm  — 71 —  u 

ir\ J 

TT  j„    J  •       1   /I 

sm  ^  o 

2 


de 


2  C^'  /sin  m(l) 
"ttJo    Vsin^ 

where  (f)=^-9,  and  7n  =  2n  +  1. 


Now  the  expression  (    .    ^j    vanishes  when 


TT  27r  Stt 
0  =  —  or  —  or  — 
^      m        m         m 


522  LAPLACE. 

and  between  each  of  these  values  it  will  be  found  that  the  ex- 
pression is  numerically  a  maximum,  and  it  is  also  a  maximum  when 
(j)  =  0.    Thus  we  may  calculate  by  Art.  957  the  value  of  the  integral 

'sm  7nd)\^  .     .  .  .  TT 

— : — ~     d6  when  the  limits  are  consecutive  multiples  of  — . 
^  sni  (p  J      ^  m 

sm  Tyicri 
The  equation  which  determines  the  maxima  values  of  — ^ — ,- 

sm<p 

is 

m,  cos  mcf)  sin  (/>  —  cos  <j)  sin  mcf) 


!• 


sin^  (j) 


0. 


It  will  be  found  that  this  is  satisfied  when  <^  =  0 ;  the  situation 
of  the  other  values  of  cf)  will  be  more  easily  discovered  by  putting 
the  equation  in  the  form 

tan  m(j)  —  m  tan  (^  =  0  : 
now  we  see  that  the  next  solution  will  lie  between  m(b  =  -—  and 

»">73"  7  77"  077" 

m^—  — ,  and  then  the  next  between  m(p  =  -r-  and  m<^  =  -^, 
and  so  on. 

We  proceed  then  to  find 

''sin  mcf)\ 


IT 

'711 


sm 


JJ 


d(f>. 


The  maximum  value  of  the  function  which  is  to  be  integrated 
occurs  when  4>  =  0,  and  is  therefore  m* ;  assume 


—  77i*e~^', 


/sin  m(f)^  * 
V  sin  (/)  , 

j  =  m*e~''; 

take  logarithms,  thus  we  obtain 


LAPLACE.  523 


Therefore  approximately 


d<t>  V6 

dt  ~^ls{m'-l)}' 

The  limits  of  ^  will  be  0  and  x  .     Hence  approximately 
2  r^  /sin  7?2(f)\*  ,^      2         w''  ^/6        r  -t^  j. 

m'  V6  (2w  +  1)'  \/3 


Laplace  next  considers  the  value  of  the  integral  with  respect 

to  <h  between  the  limits  —  and  — ,  and  then  the  value  between 
^  m  m 

the  limits  — •  and  ^ —  ,  and  so  on  ;  he  shews  that  when  5  is  a  very 
771  m 

large  number  these  definite  integrals  diminish  rapidly,  and  may 

be  neglected  in  comparison  with  the  value  obtained  for  the  limits 

0  and  — .     This  result  depends  on  the  fact  that  the  successive 
m 

Sm  'ITZCD 

numerical  maxima  values  of  — -. — r^  diminish  rapidly ;  as  we  shall 

sm  ^ 

now  shew.     At  a  numerical  maximum  we  have 

sin  vi(f)     m  cos  m(f)  m  m 


sin  ^  cos  ^         cos  0  V(l  +  ^^'^  tan^  </>)      VCcos'^  ^  +  m"^  sin^  0)  ' 

this  is  less  than  ^ — r ,  that  is  less  than    .      .  .  — ,  and  therefore 

sm  (p  sm  (p  9 

a  for^tiori  less  than  —  — ,  that  is  less  than  ^  — r . 
•^  2  <j)  2  incp 

Hence  at  the  second  maximum  —. — j-  is  less  than  -  -—  , 

sm  0  2   5 

that  is  less  than  ^ ,  and  therefore  the  ratio  of  the  second  nume- 

o 


524<  LAPLACE. 

rical  maximum  value  of  (  —. — ~]  to  the  first  is  less  than  f  J)  . 
Similarly  the  ratio  of  the  third  numerical  maximum  value  to  the 
first  is  less  than  f^j  .     And  so  on. 

Next  suppose  that  we  require  the  coefficient  of  a  in  the 
expansion  of 

[4  +  -4i  +  -^2  +...  +  -  +  1  +  «  +  •••+«""'+«""'  +  ^4'- 
[a       a         a  a  ) 

The  coefficient  of  a'"  in  this  expansion  will  be  the  same  as  the 
coefficient  of  a"*" ;  denote  the  coefficient  of  a""  by  A^..  Pat  e^^ 
for  a  and  suppose  the  expression  to  be  arranged  according  to 
cosines  of  the  multiples  of  6 ;  then  2A^  cos  r6  will  be  the  term 
corresponding  to  A^  (a*"  +  a"*").  If  we  multiply  the  expression  by 
cos  W,  and  integrate  between  the  limits  0  and  tt,  all  the  terms 
will  vanish   except  that  for  which  r  is  equal  to  I;  so  that  the 

integral  reduces  to  2Ai  j  cos^  Wd6.     Hence 


cos  WdO. 


1 

We  put;  as  before,  m  —  2n  + 1,  and  (f>  =  ^0;  thus  we  have 


As  before  assume 

/sin  m4i\^ 


c 


sin  md>Y         „  _,, 


sm 


V 


then  </)  =    ..    ,  \ — TyT ,  approximately. 


Hence  the  intoOTal  becomes 


to' 


2     "^'^'5    f^-,^^^    2?^y6    ^, 


TT 


Vis K- 1)1  J"  ^"V(«K-i)} 


LAPLACE.  525 

As  before   we  take  0  and   oo    for  the   limits  of  t,   and  thus 
neglect  all  that  part  of  the  integral  with  respect  to  0  which  is  not 


TT 


included  between  the  limits  0  and  — .     Hence  by  Art.  958  we 

m 

have  finally 

2         77ZV6         Vtt   -,-J^  (2/z  +  l)V3      -^-^, 

;;  sj[s  {m'  -  1)}     2   ^  '    ""^  ^/[n  {n  +  1)  2s7r} 

Suppose  now  that  we  require  the  sum  of  the  coefficients,  from 
that  of  a-^  to  that  of  o}  both  inclusive  ;  we  must  find  the  sum  of 

2^j+2^z.i+2^i_2+...  +  2^^  +  ^,: 

this  is  best  effected  by  the  aid  of  Euler's  Theorem ;  see  Art.  384. 
We  have  approximately 

ri  11 

r?  1  1 

therefore  ^^  u^  =  I  u^dx  +  « ^^a;  +  «  ^o  > 

therefore  2^^^^ Ug;  —  u^  =  2  I  ujix  +  u^, 

J  0 

Hence  the  required  result  is 

We  may  observe  that  Laplace  demonstrates  Euler's  Tlieorem 
in  the  manner  which  is  now  usual  in  elementary  works,  that  is  by 
the  aid  of  the  Calculus  of  Operations. 

966.     Laplace  gives  on  his  page  158  the  formula 


00 


/. 


1 


x^  ^ e^ dx 

0 

He  demonstrates  this  in  his  own  way  ;  it  is  sufficient  to  obseiTe 
that  it  may  be  obtained  by  putting  x  for  sx  in  the  integral  in  the 
numerator  of  the  left-hand  side. 


526  LAPLACE. 


Hence  he  deduces 


/•    00 

I    x^^  e-^  (e-^  -  1)"  dx 


^n  -    ^  -_o 


6-* 


:&-^  e~^  dx 


Laplace  calculates  tlie  approximate  value  of  this  expression, 
supposing  {  very  large.  He  assumes  that  the  result  which  he 
obtains  will  hold  when  the  sign  of  {  is  changed  ;  so  that  he  obtains 
an  approximate  expression  for  AV;  see  page  159  of  his  work. 
He  gives  a  demonstration  in  the  additions;  see  page  474  of  the 
Tkeorie...des  Proh.  The  demonstration  involves  much  use  of  the 
symbol  \/(-  !)•  Cauchy  gives  a  demonstration  on  page  247  of  the 
memoir  cited  in  Art.  964.  Laplace  gives  another  formula  for 
AV  on  his  page  163 ;  he  arrives  at  it  by  the  aid  of  integrals  with 
imaginary  limits,  and  then  confirms  his  result  by  a  demon- 
stration. 

967.  Laplace  says,  on  his  page  165,  that  in  the  theory  of 
chances  we  often  require  to  consider  in  the  expression  for  AV  only 
those  terms  in  which  the  quantity  raised  to  the  power  t  is  positive; 
and  accordingly  he  proceeds  to  give  suitable  approximate  formulae 
for  such  cases.  Then  he  passes  on  to  consider  specially  the  ap- 
proximate value  of  the"  expression 

Tl  [71  —  1 ) 

(n-\-r  sJnY -  n  (ii  +  r  V?i - 2)^  +  (n +  r  ^Jn- iy  -  ... , 

where  the  series  is  to  extend  only  so  long  as  the  quantities  raised 
to  the  power  yu,  are  positive,  and  />t  is  an  integer  a  little  greater  or 
a  little  less  than  n.     See  Arts.  916,  917. 

The  methods  are  of  the  kind  already  noticed ;  that  is  they  are 
not  demonstrative,  but  rest  on  a  free  use  of  the  symbol  a/ (— 1). 

A  point  should  be  noticed  with  respect  to  Laplace's  page  171. 
He  has  to  establish  a  certain  formula;  but  the  whole  difficulty  of 
the  process  is  passed  over  with  the  words  determinant  convenable- 
ment  la  constante  arhitraire.  Laplace's  formula  is  established  by 
Cauchy ;  see  page  240  of  the  memoir  cited  in  Art.  964. 

968.  In  conclusion  we  may  observe  that  this  Chapter  contains 
many  important  results,  but  it  is  to  be  regretted  that  the  demon- 


LAPLACE.  527 

strations  are  very  imperfect.  The  memoir  of  Cauchy  to  which  we 
have  referred,  is  very  laborious  and  difficult,  so  that  this  portion 
of  the  Theorie...des  Proh.  remains  in  an  unsatisfactory  state. 

969.  We  now  arrive  at  Livre  ii,  which  is  entitled  TMorie 
Generate  des  Prohahilites. 

It  will  be  understood  that  when  we  speak  of  any  Chapter  in 
Laplace's  work  without  further  specification,  we  always  mean  a 
Chapter  of  Livre  IL 

The  first  Chapter  is  entitled  Principes  generaux  de  cette  TMorie. 
This  occupies  pages  179 — 188 ;  it  gives  a  brief  statement,  with 
exemplification,  of  the  first  principles  of  the  subject. 

970.  The  second  Chapter  is  entitled  De  la  ProbcibiliU  des 
^venemens  composes  d'Svenemens  simples  dont  les  possihiliUs  respec- 
tives  sont  donnees.  This  occupies  pages  189 — 27-i  ;  it  contains  the 
solution  of  several  problems  in  direct  probability  ;  we  will  notice 
them  in  order. 

971.  The  first  problem  is  one  connected  with  a  lottery ;  see 
Arts.  291,  44^8,  4<d5,  775,  864,  910. 

The  present  discussion  adds  to  what  Laplace  had  formerly 
given  an  approximate  calculation.  The  French  lottery  was  com- 
posed of  90  numbers,  5  of  which  were  drawn  at  a  time.  Laplace 
shews  that  it  is  about  an  even  chance  that  in  86  drawingfs  all 
the  numbers  will  appear.  This  approximate  calculation  is  an 
example  of  the  formula  for  AV  given  by  Laplace  on  page  159  of 
his  work  ;  see  Art.  966. 

We  may  remark  that  Laplace  also  makes  use  of  a  rougher  ap- 
proximation originally  given  by  De  Moivre  ;  see  Art.  292. 

972.  On  his  page  201  Laplace  takes  the  problem  of  odd  and 
even;  see  Arts.  350,  865,  882. 

Laplace  adds  the  following  problem.  Suppose  that  an  urn  con- 
tains X  white  balls,  and  the  same  number  of  black  balls  ;  an  even 
number  of  balls  is  to  be  drawn  out :  required  the  probability  that 
as  many  white  balls  as  black  balls  will  be  drawn  out. 

The  whole  number  of  cases  is  found  to  be  2"^"^  —  1,  and  the 


528  LAPLACE. 

whole  number  of  favourable  cases  to  be  -^= 1 ;  the  required 


X  \x 
probability  therefore  is  the  latter  number  divided  by  the  former. 

973,  The  next  problem  is  the  Problem  of  Points.  Laplace 
treats  this  very  fully  under  its  various  modifications ;  the  dis- 
cussion occupies  his  pages  203 — 217.     See  Arts.  872,  884. 

We  will  exhibit  in  substance,  Laplace's  mode  of  investigation. 
Two  players  A  and  B  want  respectively  x  and  y  points  of  winning 
a  set  of  games  ;  their  chances  of  winning  a  single  game  are  jp  and 
q  resj^ectively,  w^here  the  sum  of  "p  and  q  is  unity  ;  the  stake  is  to 
belong  to  the  player  who  first  makes  up  his  set :  determine  the 
probabilities  in  favour  of  each  player. 

Let  </)  {x^  y)  denote  ^'s  probability.  Then  his  chance  of  win- 
ning the  next  game  is  p,  and  if  he  wins  it  his  probability  becomes 
</)  (a?  —  1,  y) ;  and  q  is  his  chance  of  losing  this  game,  and  if  he  loses 
it  his  probability  becomes  ^{x,  y  —  1)  :  thus 

^  {x,  y)  =p  ^  {x  -1,  y)  -\-  q  (\>  {x,  y  -1) (1). 

Suppose  that  </>  [x,  y)  is  the  coefficient  of  fr^  in  the  develop- 
ment according  to  powers  of  t  and  r  of  a  certain  function  u  of 
these  variables.     From  (1)  we  shall  obtain 

u-t<i>(x,  0)f-t^{0,y)  T^+^(0,  0) 

==u(pt  +  qT)-pttcl>(x,0)f-qTtcl^{0,7j)T' (2), 

where  ^  cj)  (x,  0)  f  denotes  a  summation  with  respect  to  x  from 
X  =  0  inclusive  to  x=  oo  ;  and  X  (/>  (0,  y)  r'"  denotes  a  summation 
with  respect  to  y  from  ?/  =  0  inclusive  to  y=  cc  .  In  order  to  shew 
that  (2)  is  true  we  have  to  observe  two  facts. 

First,  the  coefficient  of  any  such  term  as  Tr",  where  neither  m 
nor  n  is  less  than  unity,  is  the  same  on  both  sides  of  (2)  by  virtue 
of  (1). 

Secondly,  on  the  left-hand  side  of  (2)  such  terms  as  Tt",  where 
m  or  7i  is  less  than  unity,  cancel  each  other ;  and  so  also  do  such 
terms  on  the  right-hand  side  of  (2). 

Thus  (2)  is  fully  established.     From  (2)  we  obtain 

u —        , 

1  —j)f  —  qr 


LAPLACE.  529 

wc  may  write  this  result  thus, 

Avhere  i^(^)  and  /(r)  are  functions  of  t  and  r  respectively,  which 

are  at  present  undetermined.    By  supposing  that  the  term  in  /(t) 

vv'hich  is  independent  of  t  is  included  in  F{t),  we  may  write  the 

result  thus, 

„  =  %IO±ltM (4)_ 

1  —  pt  —  qr 

Thus  either  (3)  or  (4)  may  be  taken  as  the  general  solution  of 
the  equation  (1)  in  Finite  Differences;  and  this  general  solution 
involves  two  arbitrary  functions  which  must  be  determined  by 
sjDecial  considerations.  We  proceed  to  determine  these  functions 
in  the  present  case,  taking  the  form  (4)  which  will  be  the  most 
convenient. 

Now  A  loses  if  B  first  makes  up  his  set,  so  that  <^  {x,  0)  =  0 
for  every  value  of  x  from  unity  upwards,  and  (/>  (0,  0)  does  not 
occur,  that  is  it  may  also  be  considered  zero.  But  from  (4)  it 
follows  that  (j)  (x,  0)  is  the  coefficient  of  f  in  the  development 

of  ^^^   ;  therefore  v  (t)  =  0. 

Again,  A  wins  if  he  first  makes  up  his  set,  so  that  cj)  (0,  y)  =  1 
for  every  value  of  i/  from  unity  upwards.     But  from  (4)  it  follows 

that  (j)  (0,  y)  is  the  coefficient  of  t^  in  the  development  of  r-^ 

so  that 

Tyjr  (t)  _      T 


qr 


therefore 

Thus  finally 


1- 

qr      1 

-t' 

T^fr  (t) 

t(1. 
1- 

• 

-  T 

■t(1- 

qr) 

{l-T){l-pt-qT) 


Now  <^{x,y)  is  the  coefficient  of  fr'  in  the  development  of  w. 
First  expand  according  to  powers  of  t ;  thus  we  obtain  for  the 

34 


530  LAPLACE. 


«. 


p  T 


coefficient   of  f  the  expression        _  J^  .^  _     y .     Then  expand 

this  expression  according  to  powers  of  r,  and  we  finally  obtain  for 
the  coefficient  of  fj^ 


This  is  therefore  the  probability  in  favour  of  A  ;  and  that  in 

favour  of  JB  may  be  obtained  by  interchanging  p  with  q  and  x 

with  ?/. 

The  result  is  identical  with  the  second  of  the  two  formuloe 

which  we  have  given  in  Art.  172. 

97*i.     The  investigation  just  given  is  in  substance  Laplace's ; 

he  takes  the  particular  case  in  which  p  =  -^  and  q  =  ^',  but  this 

makes  no  difference  in  principle.     But  there  is  one  important 
difference.     At  the  stage  where  we  have 

F{t)  +/(t) 


u  = 


1  —pt  —  qr 

Laplace  puts 

fir) 


u  = 


1  —jyi  —  qr 

This  is  an  error,  it  arises  from  a  false  formula  given  by  Laplace 
on  his  page  82;  see  Art.  955.  Laplace's  error  amounts  to  neg- 
lectinsc  the  considerations  involved  in  the  second  of  the  facts  on 
which  equation  (2)  of  the  preceding  Article  depends :  this  kind 
of  neglect  has  been  not  uncommon  with  those  who  have  used  or 
expounded  the  method  of  Generating  Functions. 

975.  We  will  continue  the  discussion  of  the  Problem  of  Points, 
and  suppose  that  there  are  more  than  two  players.  Let  the  first 
player  want  x^  i^oints,  the  second  x^  points,  the  third  x^  points, 
and  so  on.  Let  their  respective  chances  of  winning  a  single  game 
^^  1\' 2\>  1\^  • ' •  Let  cj)  (x^,  x^,  x^,  . . .)  denote  the  probability  in 
favour  of  the  first  player.  Then,  as  in  Art.  973,  we  obtain  the 
equation 


LAPLACE.  531 

Suppose  that  cj)  {x^,  x^,  x^,  ...)  is  the  coefficient  of  ?f/i  t^'^^ts^'s  ... 
in  the  development  of  a  function  u  of  these  variables.  Laplace 
then  proceeds  thus.     From  (1)  he  passes  to 

?^  =  w(M+M  +  M+---) (2)' 

and  then  he  deduces 

i=M+M+M  + O^)- 


Hence 


therefore 


,  ^1  (^1  + 1) 


1.2 


(M  +  M+--0' 


cc,  (a?,  +  1)  (x,  +  2)  ,  ,  . . 


+ 


Now  the  coefficient  of  t^t^^^t^^...    in  — ^  is  ^  (a^^,  ajg,  cCg,  ...)• 

Let  7i:w;:)^*i  i^"*  t^^ . . .  denote  any  term  of  the  right-hand  member 
of  the  last  equation.  Then  the  coefficient  of  t^  t,^2  t^a ...  in  this 
term  will  be  hp^i <f> (0,  x^—m,  x^—7i,...).  But  cj) (0,  x^—  m,  x^—n,...) 
is  equal  to  unity,  for  if  the  first  player  wants  no  points  he  is  en- 
titled to  the  stake.  Moreover  we  must  reject  all  the  values  of 
<f>  if),  x^  —  m,  x^  —  n, ...)  in  which  m  is  equal  to  or  greater  than  x^^ 
in  which  n  is  equal  to  or  greater  than  x^,  and  so  on;  for  these 
terms  in  fact  do  not  exist,  that  is  must  be  considered  to  be  zero. 
Hence  finally 

^  (a?j,  OJg,  a-g, . . .)  =2\^'  |l  +  a?,  {p^  +793  +  . . .) 

* !■ 

34^—2 


532  LAPLACE. 

provided  we  reject  all  terms  in  wliich  the  power  of  p^  surpasses 
x^  —  1,  in  which  the  power  oi  p^  surpasses  x^  —  1,  and  so  on. 

Now  on  this  process  of  Laplace's  we  remark :  '    . 

First,  the  equation  (2)  is  not  true ;  as  in  Art.  973  we  ought  to 
allow  for  terms  in  which  one  or  more  of  the  variables  x^,x^,x^,... 
is  zero ;  and  therefore  additional  terms  ought  to  be  placed  in  each 
member  of  equation  (2)  of  the  present  Article,  like  those  in  equa- 
tion (2)  of  Article  973. 

Secondly,  Laplace's  treatment  of  his  equation  (3)  is  unintel- 
ligible, as  we  have  already  remarked  in  a  similar  case ;  see 
Art.  952.  By  making  use  of  the  Calculus  of  Operations  we  might 
however  translate  Laplace's  process  into  another  free  from  ob- 
jection. 

976.  At  this  stage  we  shall  find  it  convenient  to  introduce  an 
account  of  the  fourth  Supplement  to  the  Theorie.,.des  Prohahilites. 
This  supplement  contains  28  pages.  Laplace  begins  with  a  few 
remarks  on  Generating  Functions;  he  gives  the  correct  formula 
for  the  solution  of  an  equation  in  Finite  Differences  for  which  he 
had  formerly  given  an  incorrect  formula:  see  Art.  955.  He  does 
not  refer  to  the  Theorie...des  Froh.  nor  take  any  notice  of  the 
discrepancy  of  the  two  formulae.  He  says,  on  page  4  of  the  Sup- 
plement, 

Un  des  principaux  avantages  de  cette  maniere  d'integrer  les  equa- 
tions aux  differences  partielles,  consiste  en  ce  que  I'analyse  algebrique 
fournissant  divers  moyens  pour  developper  les  fonctions,  on  peut  choisir 
celui  qui  convient  le  mieux  a  la  question  proposee.  La  solution  des 
]>roblemes  suivans,  par  le  Comte  de  Lai^lace,  mon  fils,  et  les  considera- 
tions qu'il  y  a  jointes,  repandront  un  nouveau  jour  sur  le  calcul  des 
fonctions  generatrices. 

We  have  therefore  to  ascribe  all  the  rest  of  the  fourth  Sup- 
plement to  Laplace's  son. 

977.  The  main  part  of  the  fourth  Supplement  consists  of  the 
solution  of  problems  which  may  be  considered  as  generalisations  of 
the  Problem  of  Points.  There  are  three  of  these  problems ;  we 
will  enunciate  them. 


LAPLACE.  533 

I.  A  player  A  draws  a  ball  from  an  urn  containing  white 
balls  and  black  balls ;  his  chance  of  drawing  a  white  ball  is  p, 
and  his  chance  of  drawing  a  black  ball  is  q :  after  the  ball  has 
been  drawn  it  is  replaced.  Then  a  second  player  B  draws  a  ball 
from  a  second  urn  contairing  white  balls  and  black  balls;  his 
chance  of  drawing  a  white  ball  is  p,  and  his  chance  of  drawing 
a  black  ball  is  q  :  after  the  ball  has  been  drawn  it  is  replaced. 
The  two  players  continue  thus  to  draw  alternately  a  ball,  each 
from  his  own  urn,  and  to  replace  the  ball  after  it  has  been 
drawn.  If  a  player  draws  a  white  ball  he  counts  a  point ;  if  he 
draws  a  black  ball  he  counts  nothing.  Suppose  that  A  wants  x 
points,  and  B  wants  x  points  to  complete  an  assigned  set,  required 
the  probabilities  in  favour  of  each  player. 

II.  Suppose  A  draws  from  an  urn  in  which  there  are  balls 
of  three  kinds ;  for  a  ball  of  the  first  kind  he  counts  two  points,  for 
a  ball  of  the  second  kind  he  counts  one  point,  and  for  a  ball  of  the 
third  kind  he  counts  no  point:  let  his  chances  he p>,p)^,  and  q  for 
the  three  cases. 

Similarly  let  B  draw  from  a  second  urn  containing  similar 
balls  ;  let^',  j9j',  and  q  be  his  chances  for  the  three  cases.  Then, 
as  before,  we  require  the  probabilities  for  each  player  of  his 
making  up  an  assigned  set  of  points  before  his  adversary  makes 
up  an  assigned  set. 

III.  An  urn  contains  a  known  number  of  black  balls,  and  a 
known  number  of  white  balls ;  a  ball  is  drawn  and  not  replaced ; 
then  another  ball,  and  so  on :  required  the  probability  that  a 
given  number  of  white  balls  will  be  drawn  before  another  given 
number  of  black  balls. 

These  three  problems  are  solved  by  the  method  of  Generating 
Functions  used  carefully  and  accurately ;  that  is,  the  terms  which 
are  required  to  make  the  equations  true  are  given,  and  not 
omitted.  See  Art.  97^.  After  the  problems  are  solved  generally 
particular  cases  are  deduced. 

The  student  of  the  fourth  Supplement  will  have  to  bear  in 
mind  that  in  the  first  problem  p  +  q  =  l  and  p?'  +  2=1*  ^^^  ^^ 
the  second  problem  p  +p)^  +  ^  =  1,    p'  +p^  -\-  q  =1, 


534  LAPLACE. 

978.  After  the  solutions  of  these  problems  we  have  a  few 
pages  headed  Remarque  sw  les  fonctions  generatrices ;  and  this  is 
the  part  of  the  fourth  Supplement  with  which  we  are  chiefly 
interested.  It  is  here  observed  that  in  a  case  like  that  of  our 
Art.  975;  the  equation  (2)  is  not  an  accurate  deduction  from  equa- 
tion (1)  ;  for  additional  terms  ought  to  be  added  to  each  side,  in 
the  manner  of  our  Art.  973. 

There  is  however  a  mistake  at  the  top  of  page  24  of  the  fourth 
Supplement :  instead  of  adding  a  function  of  t,  two  functions  must 
be  added,  one  of  t  and  the  other  of  t'. 

The  fourth  Supplement  then  proceeds  thus,  on  its  page  24  : 

Faute  d' avoir  egard  a  ces  fonctions,  on  j^eut  tomber  dans  des 
erreurs  graves,  en  se  servant  de  ce  moyen  pour  integrer  les  equations 
aux  differences  partielles.  Par  cette  meme  raison,  la  marche  suivie  dans 
la  solution  des  problemes  des  n"^^  8  et  10  du  second  livre  de  la  Theorie 
analytique  des  Probabilites  n'est  nullement  rigoureuse,  et  semble  impliquer 
contradiction,  en  ce  qu'elle  etablit  une  liaison  entre  les  variables  qui 
sont  et  doivent  etre  toujours  independantes.  Sans  entrer  dans  les 
considerations  particulieres  qui  ont  pu  la  faire  reussir  ici,  et  qu'il  est 
aise  de  saisir,  nous  allons  faire  voir  que  la  metliode  d'integration  ex- 
posee  au  commencement  de  ce  Supplement  s'applique  egalement  a  ces 
questions,  et  les  resout  avec  non  moins  de  simplicite. 

The  problem  referred  to  as  contained  in  No.  8  of  the 
TMorie...des  Proh.  is  that  which  we  have  given  in  Art.  975; 
the  problem  referred  to  as  contained  in  No.  10  of  the  Theorie...  des 
Proh.  is  that  which  we  shall  notice  in  Art.  980.  The  fourth 
Supplement  gives  solutions  of  these  problems  by  the  accurate  use 
of  Generating  Functions,  in  the  manner  of  our  Art.  973. 

Thus  as  Laplace  himself  attached  the  fourth  Supplement  to 
his  work,  we  may  conclude  that  he  admitted  the  solutions  in 
question  to  be  unsound.  We  consider  that  they  are  unsound,  and 
in  fact  unintelligible,  as  they  are  presented  by  Laplace ;  but  on 
the  other  hand,  we  believe  that  they  may  be  readily  translated 
into  the  language  of  the  Calculus  of  Operations,  and  thus  become 
clear  and  satisfactory.     See  Art.  952. 

979.  We  return  from  the  fourth  Supplement  to  the 
Theorie... des  Proh.  itself.     Laplace's  next  problem  is  that  which 


LAPLACE.  535 

is   connected  with  the  game  which  is  called  Treize  or  Rencontre ; 
see  Arts.  162,  280,  286,  430,  Q±Q. 

Laplace  devotes  his  pages  217 — 225  to  this  problem  ;  he  gives 
the  solution,  and  then  applies  his  method  of  approximation  in 
order  to  obtain  numerical  results  when  very  high  numbers  are 
involved. 

980.  Laplace  takes  next  on  his  pages  225 — 238  the  problem 
of  the  Duration  of  Play.  The  results  were  enunciated  by  De 
Moivre  and  demonstrated  by  Lagrange ;  Laplace  has  made  great 
use  of  Lagrange's  memoir  on  the  subject  ;  see  Arts.  311,  583, 
588,  863,  885,  921.  We  may  observe  that  before  Laplace  gives 
his  analytical  solution  he  says,  Ce  probleme  pent  etre  resolu 
avec  facilite  par  le  precede  suivant  qui  est  en  quelque  sorte, 
mecanique ;  the  process  which  he  gives  is  due  to  De  Moivre ; 
it  occurs  on  page  203  of  the  Doctrine  of  Chances.  See  also 
Art.  303.  In  the  course  of  the  investigation,  Laplace  gives  a 
process  of  the  kind  we  have  already  noticed,  which  is  criticised  in 
the  fourth  Supplement ;  see  Art.  978. 

981.  Laplace  takes  next  on  his  pages  238 — 2-17  the  problem 
which  we  have  called  Waldegrave's  problem ;  see  Arts.  210,  249, 
295,  348. 

There  are  n-\-l  players  C^,  G^,  ...  (7„^j.  First  C^  and  Cg  play 
together ;  the  loser  deposits  a  shilling  in  a  common  stock,  and  the 
winner  plays  with  C^ ;  the  loser  again  deposits  a  shilling,  and  the 
winner  plays  with  C^\  the  process  is  continued  until  some  one 
player  has  beaten  in  succession  all  the  rest,  the  turn  of  C^  coming 
on  again  after  that  of  (7„^j.  The  winner  is  to  take  all  the  money 
in  the  common  stock. 

Laplace  determines  the  probability  that  the  play  will  terminate 
precisely  at  the  x^^'^  game,  and  also  the  probability  that  it  will 
terminate  at  or  before  the  ic^'*  game.  He  also  determines  the 
probability  that  the  r^^  player  will  win  the  money  j)recisely  at  the 
x^^  game ;  that  is  to  say,  he  exhibits  a  complex  algebraical  func- 
tion of  a  variable  t  which  must  be  expanded  in  powers  of  x 
and  the  coefficient  of  t''  taken.  He  then  deduces  a  general  ex- 
pression for  the  advantage  of  the  r*^  player. 

The  part  of  the  solution  which  is  new  in  Laplace's  discussion 


536  LAPLACE. 

is  that  which  determines  the  probability  that  the  r^^  player  will- 
win  the  money  precisely  at  the  x^^  game ;  Nicolas  Bernoulli  had 
confined    himself  to   the   probability  which    each  player  has  of 
winning  the  money  on  the  whole. 

982.  We  will  give,  after  Laplace,  the  investigation  of  the 
probability  that  the  play  will  terminate  precisely  at  the  x^^ 
game. 

Let  z^  denote  this  probability.  In  order  that  the  play  may 
terminate  at  the  x^^  game,  the  player  who  enters  into  play  at  the 
{x  —  n-\-Vf^  game  must  win  this  game  and  the  n  —  1  following 
games. 

Suppose  that  the  winner  of  the  money  starts  with  a  player 
who  has  won  only  one  game ;  let  P  denote  the  probability  of  this 

P      . 

event ;   then  —  will  be  the  corresponding  probability  that  the 

play  will  terminate  at  the  x^^  game.     But  the  probability  that  the 
play  will  terminate  at  the  {x  —  iy^  game,  that   is  z^_^,  is  equal 

P  .     . 

to  ^Tpi .     For  it  is  necessary  to  this  end  that  a  player  who  has 

already  won  one  game  just  before  the  {x  —  n  +  Vf^  game  should 
win  this  game  and  the  n  —  ^  following  games  j  and  the  probabilities 

of  these  component  events  being  respectively   P  and  ^^^^i ,   the 

.      P 

probability  of  the  compound  event  is  ^^^ .     Thus 

P      1 

— V     • 

and  therefore  ^  z^_^  is  the  probability  that  the  play  will  terminate 

Li 

at  the  fl?*^  game,  relative  to  this  case. 

Next  suppose  that  the  winner  of  the  money  starts  with  a  player 
who  has  won  two  games ;  let  P'  denote  the  probability  of  this 

P' 

event ;  then  -^  will  be  the  corresponding  probability  that  the  play 

P' 

will  terminate  at  the  x^"^  game.     And  -^^  =  z^_^ :  for  in  order  that 

the  play  should  terminate  at  the  (ic— 2)"*  game  it  is  necessary  that 
a  player  who  has  already  won  two  games  just  before  the  (a;  — 72+ 1)"' 


LAPLACE.  537 

game  should  win  this,  game  and  the  n  —  2  following  games.     Thus 

F'      1 

and  therefore  ^  z^_^  is  the  probability  that  the  play  will  terminate 

at  the  ic*^  sfame  relative  to  this  case. 

By  proceeding  thus,  and  collecting  all  the  partial  probabilities 
we  obtain 

1  1  )_  1  n\ 

Suppose  that  z^  is  the  coefficient  of  f  in  the  expansion  accord- 
ing to  powers  of  ^  of  a  certain  function  u  of  this  variable.  Then 
from  (1)  we  have,  as  in  Art.  937, 

F(t) 


u  = 


111  1 

-*•       2  "      92  ''        2^  * "       2'*"'^ 


where  -F  (^)  is  a  function  of  t  which  is  at  present  undetermined. 

Now  if  (1)  were  true  for  x  =  n  SiS  well  as  for  higher  values  of 
n,  the  function  F(t)  would  be  of  the  degree  n  —  1.  But  (1)  does 
not  hold  when  x  —  n,  for  in  forming  (1)  the  player  who  wins  the 
money  was  supposed  to  start  against  an  opponent  who  had  won 
one  game  at  least ;  so  that  in  (1)  we  cannot  suppose  x  to  be  less 
than  n-\-l.  Hence  the  function  F  [t)  will  be  of  the  degree  n, 
and  we  may  put 

a^  +  ait  +  ctf  +  .  • .  +  a.f' 


u  = 


111  1 


Now  the  play  cannot  terminate  before  the  ?i*''  game,  and  the  pro- 
bability of  its  terminating  at  the  n^^  game  is  ^^^ ;  therefore  a^ 

vanishes  for  values  of  x  less  than  n,  and  a,,  =  — — • .     Thus 


538  LxlPLACE. 

The  coefficient  of  f  in  the  expansion  of  u  in  powers  of  t  gives 
the  probabiHty  that  the  play  will  terminate  at  the  x^^  game. 

The  probability  that  the  play  will  terminate  at  or  before  the 
x^^  game  will  be  the  sum  of  the  coefficients  of  f  and  of  the  inferior 
jDOwers  of  t  in  the  expansion  of  u,  which  will  be  equal  to  the  co- 

u 

efficient  of  f  in  the  expansion  of- ;  that  is,  it  will  be  the  co- 
efficient of  f  in  the  ex^Dansion  of 

1  f  (2  -  t) 

This  expression  is  equal  to 

1  r(2-o  f  f  f r  \ 

¥  {l-tf  \        T  (1  -  0  "^  2'^'  (1  -  tf     2^''(l-/)-^'^  ""J  ' 
The  T^^  term  of  this  development  is 

(- 1)*--^  (2  - 1)  r 


9r/i, 


r+l   > 


that  is 


(        1)  l^™-!    (^1 


ty^^        ^rn  ^^  _  ^y^lj  • 


The  expansion  in  powers  of  t  of  this  r*  term   may  now  be 
readily  effected  ;  the  coefficient  of  f  will  be 

f    1     \ic-\-r  —  rii        \  \x  -\-r  —  rii  —  1 
(-    )      I  2^^  \x-rn\r  ~  W'  \x-rn-\  [T  j   ' 


/     2y-i  \x  -\-r  —  rn  —  1 

that  is  ^-TTri—  ,  {x  —  rn  +  2r). 

^"^"^  x  —  rn\r        ^  ^ 


The  final  result  is  that  the  probability  that  the  play  will  termi- 
nate at  or  before  the  x^^  game,  is  represented  by  as  many  terms 
of  the  following  series  as   there  are   units  in   the   integer  next 

below  - : 
n 

1    2   3~2^ ^    -  o;i  +  uj  —  . . . 


LAPLACE.  539 

The  sum  of  the  coefficients  of  every  power  of  t  up  to  infinity 
in  the  expansion  of  u  will  represent  the  probability  that  the  play 
will  terminate  if  there  be  no  limit  assigned  to  the  number  of  games. 
But  the  sum  of  these  coefficients  will  be  equal  to  the  value  of  i6 
when  t  is  made  equal  to  unity ;  and  this  value  of  u  is  unity.  Hence 
we  infer  that  the  probability  of  the  termination  of  the  play  may 
be  made  as  near  to  unity  as  we  please  by  allowing  a  sufficient 
number  of  games. 

983.  In  Laplace's  own  solution  no  notice  is  taken  of  the  fact 
that  equation  (1)  does  not  hold  for  x  =  n.  Professor  De  Morgan 
remarks  in  a  note  to  Art.  52  of  the  Theory  of  Probabilities  in  the 
EnciJclopcBdia  Metropolitana, 

Laplace  (p.  240)  has  omitted  all  allusion  to  this  circumstance  ;  and 
the  omission  is  highly  characteristic  of  his  method  of  writing.  ISTo  one 
was  more  sure  of  giving  the  result  of  an  analytical  process  correctly,  and 
no  one  ever  took  so  little  care  to  point  out  the  various  small  considera- 
tions on  which  correctness  depends.  His  Theorie  cles  Probabilites  is  by 
very  much  the  most  difficult  mathematical  work  we  have  ever  met 
with,  and  prmcipally  from  this  circumstance :  the  Mecanique  Celeste  has 
its  full  share  of  the  same  sort  of  difficulty;  but  the  analysis  is  less  intri- 
cate. 

984.  We  may  observe  that  as  Laplace  continues  his  discussion 
of  Waldegrave's  problem  he  arrives  at  the  following  equation  in 
Finite  Differences, 

1 

i/r,  X        yr-\ ,  x-1  "f"  ~e)n  U i\  x-n        ^  j 

in  integrating  this,  although  his  final  result  is  correct,  his  process  is 
unsatisfactory,  because  it  depends  upon  an  error  we  have  already 
indicated.     See  Art.  955. 

r 

985.  Laplace's  next  problem  is  that  relating  to  a  run  of 
events  which  was  discussed  by  De  Moivre  and  Condorcet ;  see 
Arts.  325,  G77  :  this  problem  occupies  Laplace's  pages  247 — 253. 

Let  2^  denote  the  chance  of  the  happening  of  the  event  in  a 
single  trial ;  let  </>  {x)  denote  the  probability  that  in  x  trials  the 


540  LAPLACE. 

event  will  happen  i  times  in  succession.     Then  from  equation  (1) 
of  Art.  678  by  changing  the  notation  we  have 

^  (x)  ^p'+p'-'  (1  -p)  cj,  (x-i)  -\-p'-'  (1  -p)  ct>{x-i-^  1)  +  ... 

,..+p{l-p)c^{x-2)  +  (l^p)<t>(x-l) (1). 

Laplace  takes  z^  to  denote  the  probability  that  the  run  will 
finish  at  the  x^^  trial,  and  not  before ;  then  he  obtains 

^x  =  (1     p)  1^.-1  +  P^^,  +P\-,  +  . . .  +  p"'  ^x- j (2). 

"VVe  may  deduce  (2)  thus ;  it  is  obvious  that 

z^  =  (f>{x)-(f){x-l); 

hence  in    (1)    change   x  into   x  —  1    and   subtract,   and    we   ob- 
tain (2). 

Laplace  proceeds  nearly  thus.  If  the  run  is  first  completed 
at  the  x^^  trial  the  (x—iy^  trial  must  have  been  unfavourable,  and 
the  following  i  trials  favourable.  Laplace  then  makes  ^  distinct 
cases. 

I.     The  (x  —  i—  \y^  trial  unfavourable. 

IL  The  {x-i-iy^  favourable;  and  the  (a;-f-2y^  un- 
favourable. 

Ill  The  [x-i-  \y^  and  the  {x  -  i-  2)"^  favourable,  and  the 
{x — {—  3)  ''^  unfavou  rable. 

IV.  The  {^x-i-Vf\  the  {x-i-2f\  and  the  {x-i-Zf 
favourable;  and  the  (a;— ^  — 4)^^   unfavourable. 

And  so  on. 

Let  us  take  one  of  these  cases,  say  IV.  Let  P^  denote  the 
probability  of  this  case  existing ;  then  will 

For  in  this  case  a  run  of  3  has  been  obtained,  and  if  this  be 
followed  by  a  run  of  /— 3,  of  which  the  chance  is  p^'"^,  we  obtain 
a  run  of  i  ending  at  the  [x  —  4)*^  trial. 

Now  the  part  of  z^  which  arises  from  this  case  IV.  is  FJ(\.  —p)  j/\ 
for  we  require  an   unfavourable  result  at   the  {x  —  if^  trial,   of 


LAPIACE.  541 

which  the  chance  is  1—p,  and  then  a  run  of  t.     Thus  the  part 
of  z^  is 


'X 

Z 


^(1-i^)/^  or^/(l-^;)^,_,. 


We  have  said  that  Laplace  adopts  nearly  the  method  we  have 
given ;  but  he  is  rather  obscure.  In  the  method  we  have  given 
P^  denotes  the  probability  of  the  following  compound  event :  no 
run  of  i  before  the  (ic  — /— 4)^^  trial,  the  (a?— ^— 4)^^  trial  un- 
favourable, and  then  the  next  three  trials  favourable.  Similarly 
our  Pg  would  denote  the  probability  of  the  following  compound 
event;  no  run  of  i  before  the  (a?  — ^  —  2)^^  trial,  the  {x—i—Tf^ 
trial  unfavourable,  and  the  next  trial  favourable.  Laplace  says, 
Nommons  P'  la  probability  qu'il  n'arrivera  pas  au  coup  x  —  i—% 
Now  Laplace  does  not  formally  say  that  there  is  to  be  no  run  of 
i  before  the  {x  —  i—  2)^^  trial ;  but  this  must  be  understood.  Then 
his  P  agrees  with  our  Pj  if  we  omit  the  last  of  the  three  clauses 
which  form  our  account  of  the  probability  represented  by  Pg ;  so 
that  in  fact  pP'  with  Laplace  denotes  the  same  as  F^  with  us. 

Laplace  gives  the  integral  of  the  equation  (2),  and  finally  ob- 
tains the  same  result  as  we  have  exhibited  in  Art.  325. 

986.  Laplace  then  proceeds  to  find  the  probability  that  one 
of  two  players  should  have  a  run  of  i  successes  before  the  other ; 
this  investigation  adds  nothing  to  what  Condorcet  had  given,  but 
is  more  commodious  in  form.  Laplace's  result  on  his  page  250 
will  be  found  on  examination  to  d^^t^o,  with  what  we  have  griven 
in  Art.  680,  after  Condorc3t. 

Laplace  then  supplies  some  new  matter,  in  which  he  considers 
the  expectation  of  each  player  supposing  that  after  failiug  he 
deposits  a  franc,  and  that  the  sum  of  the  deposits  is  taken  by  him 
who  first  has  a  run  of  i  successes. 

987.  Laplace's  next  problem  is  the  following.  An  urn  con- 
tains 71  +  1  balls  marked  respectively  0,  1,  ...  w ;  a  ball  is  drawn 
and  replaced :  required  the  probability  that  after  i  drawings  the 
sum  of  the  numbers  drawn  will  be  s.  This  problem  and  applica- 
tions of  it  occupy  pages  253 — 261.     See  Arts.  888,  915. 

The  problem  is  due  to  De  Moivre ;  see  Arts.  149,  364.  La- 
place's solution  of  the  problem  is  very  laborious.     We  will  pass  to 


542  LAPLACE. 

the  application  which  Laphxce  makes  of  the  result  to  the  subject 
of  the  planes  of  motion  of  the  planets. 

By  proceeding  as  in  Art.  148,  we  find  that  the  probability  that 
after  i  drawings  the  sum  of  the  numbers  drawn  will  be  s  is  the 
coefficient  of  x^  in  the  expansion  of 

— ^  (1  -  ic^^y  (1  -  xY\ 

Thus  we  obtain  for  the  required  probability 
1        {\i+s-l      i     U*+s-n-2 


[n-^VfMi-l  \s       1  [i:il  Lf^i^^ij^l 


i[i-\)      h'  +  g-2;2~3 


1.2       ^-l    5-2^ 


If  the  balls  are  marked  respectively  0,  Q,  2^,  8^,  ,.,nd,  this 
expression  gives  the  probability  that  after  i  drawings  the  sum  of 
the  numbers  drawn  will  be  sQ. 

Now  suppose  0  to  become  indefinitely  small,  and  n  and  5  to 
become  indefinitely  great.  The  above  expression  becomes  ulti- 
mately 


i-\  \\nl         \\n        1     ^     1.2     \n        j         '"     n 


s  1 

Let  -  be  denoted  by  x,  and  -  by  dx,  so  that  we  obtain 


n  "      '  n 


this  expression  may  be  regarded  as  the  conclusion  of  the  follow- 
ing problem.  The  numerical  result  at  a  single  trial  must  lie 
between  0  and  1,  and  all  fractional  values  are  equally  probable  : 
determine  the  probability  that  after  { trials  the  sum  of  the  results 
obtained  will  lie  between  x  and  x  +  dx^  where  dx  is  indefinitely 
small. 

Hence  if  we  require  the  probability  that  after  i  trials  the  sum 
of  the  results  obtained  will  lie  between  x^  and  x^,  we  must  inte- 


LAPLACE.  543 

grate  the  above  expresBion  between  the  limits  x^  and  0*^, ;   thus 
we  obtain 

i|-.;-|K-i)'+^(-.-2)'-... 


Each  series,  like  the  others  in  the  present  Article,  is  to  be 
continued  only  so  long  as  the  quantities  which  are  raised  to  the 
power  {  are  positive. 

We  might  have  obtained  this  result  more  rapidly  by  using 
Art.  3G4  as  our  starting  point  instead  of  Art.  148. 

At  the  beginning  of  the  year  1801,  the  sum  of  the  inclinations 
of  the  orbits  of  the  ten  planets  to  the  ecliptic  was  914187 
French  degrees,  that  is  '914187  of  a  right  angle;  suppose  that  for 
each  planet  any  inclination  between  zero  and  a  right  angle  had 
been  equally  likely  :  required  the  probability  that  the  sum  of  the 
inclinations  would  have  been  between  0  and  "914187  of  a  right 
angle.     By  the   preceding  expression  we   obtain   for   the   result 

-^  (-914187)'',   that  is  about  '00000011235. 


Speaking  of  this  probability,  Laplace  says  : 

...  Elle  est  deja  tres-petite ;  mais  il  faut  encore  la  combiner  avec 
la  probability  d'une  circonstance  tres-remarqiiable  dans  le  systeme  du 
monde,  et  qui  consiste  en  ce  que  toutes  les  planetes  se  meuvent  dans  le 
meme  sens  que  la  terre.     Si  les  mouvemens  directs  et  retrogrades  sont 

supposes  ^galement  possibles,  cette  demiere  probabilite  est  (     )    ;    il 

/IV" 
faut  done  multiplier  '00000011235  par  f- )  ,  pour  avoir  la  probabilite 

que  tous  les  mouvemens  des  planetes  et  de  la  terre  seront  diriges  dans  le 

meme  sens,  et  que  la  somme  de  leurs  inclinaisons  a  I'orbite  de  la  terre, 

2-0972 
sera  comprise  dans  les  limites  zero  et  91*''4187;  on  aurn  ainsi  jjt^i^ 

pour  cette  probabilite ;  ce  qui  donne  1  —    ^,io   pour  la  probabilite  que 

cela  n'a  pas  du  avoir  lieu,  si  toutes  les  inclinaisons,  ainsi  que  les  mouve- 
mens directs  et  retrogrades,  ont  ete  egalement  faciles.     Cette  probabilite 


544)  LAPLACE. 

approclie  tellement  de  la  certitude,  que  le  resultat  observe  devient 
invraisemblable  dans  cette  liypothese ;  ce  resultat  indique  done  avec 
une  tres-grande  probabilite,  I'existence  d'une  cause  primitive  qui  a  deter- 
mine les  mouvemens  des  planetes  a  se  rapprocber  du  plan  de  I'ecliptique, 
ou  plus  naturellement,  du  plan  de  I'equateur  solaire,  et  a  se  mouvoir 
dans  le  sens  de  la  rotation  du  soleil... 

Laplace  then  mentions  other  circumstances  which  strengthen 
his  conclusion,  such  as  the  fact  that  the  motion  of  the  satellites  is 
also  in  the  same  direction  as  that  of  the  planets. 

A  similar  investigation  applied  to  the  observed  comets  does 
not  give  any  ground  for  suspecting  the  existence  of  a  primitive 
cause  which  has  affected  the  inclination  of  their  planes  of  motion 
to  the  plane  of  the  ecliptic.  See  however  Cournot's  Exposition  de 
la  Theorie  des  Chances  . . .  page  270. 

Laplace's  conclusion  with  respect  to  the  motions  of  the  planets 
has  been  accepted  by  very  eminent  writers  on  the  subject ;  for 

example  by  Poisson :  see  his  Recherches  sur  la  Proh page  802. 

But  on  the  other  hand  two  most  distinguished  philosophers  have 
recorded  their  dissatisfaction ;  see  Professor  Boole's  Laws  of 
Thought,  page  864,  and  a  note  by  K.  L.  Ellis  in  The  Works  of 
Francis  Bacon ...  Vol  L  1857,  page  848. 

988.  Laplace  devotes  his  pages  262 — 274  to  a  very  remark- 
able process  and  examples  of  it ;  see  Art.  892.  The  following  is 
his  enunciation  of  the  problem  which  he  solves  : 

Soient  i  quantites  variables  et  positives  t,  t^,...ti_^  dont  la  somme  soit 
s,  et  dont  la  loi  de  possibilite  soit  connue ;  on  propose  de  trouver  la 
somme  des  produits  de  cliaque  valeur  que  pent  recevoir  une  fonction 
donnee  i(/(t,  t^,  t^,  (fee.)  de  ces  variables,  multipliee  par  la  probabilite 
correspondante  a  cette  valeur. 

The  problem  is  treated  in  a  very  general  way;  the  laws  of 
possibility  are  not  assumed  to  be  continuous,  nor  to  be  the  same 
for  the  different  variables.  The  whole  investigation  is  a  charac- 
teristic specimen  of  the  great  powers  of  Laplace,  and  of  the  brevity 
and  consequent  difficulty  of  his  expositions  of  his  methods. 

Laplace  applies  his  result  to  determine  the  probability  that 
the  sum  of  the  errors  of  a  given  number  of  observations  shall  lie 
between  assigned  limits,  supposing  the  law  of  the  facility  of  error  in 


LAPLACE.  545 

a  single  observation  to  be  known :  Laplace's  formula  when  applied 
by  him  to  a  special  case  coincides  with  that  which  we  have  given 
in  Art.  567  from  Lagrange. 

989.  An  example  is  given  by  Laplace,  on  his  page  271,  which 
we  may  conveniently  treat  independently  of  his  general  investi- 
gation, with  which  he  himself  connects  it.  Let  there  be  a  number 
n  of  points  ranged  in  a  straight  line,  and  let  ordinates  be  drawn 
at  these  points ;  the  sum  of  these  ordinates  is  to  be  equal  to  s : 
moreover  the  first  ordinate  is  not  to  be  greater  than  the  second, 
the  second  not  greater  than  the  third,  and  so  on.  Required  the 
mean  value  of  the  r*^  ordinate. 

Let  z^  denote  the  first  ordinate,  let  z^  +  z,^  denote  the  second, 
^1  +  ^2+  ^3  ^^^  third,  and  so  on :  thus  z^,  z^,  z^, ...  z^  are  all  posi- 
tive variables,  and  since  the  sum  of  the  ordinates  is  s  we  have 

nz^-^{n-l)z^-\-  (n-2)  z^+  ...  +z,,  =  s (1). 

The  mean  value  of  the  r*^  ordinate  will  be 

{z^-{-z^+  ...  +Zr)  dz^dz^,..  dz^ 


ctz^  (^z~ . . .  CIZ^^ 


where  the  integrations  are  to  be  extended  over  all  positive  values 
of  the  variables  consistent  with  the  limitation  (1). 

Put  nz^  =  x^,  (ii  —  l)z^  =  x^,  and  so  on.     Then  our  expression 
becomes 

...  p  +  — ^H--^  +  ...  -\ ^^^--^]dx^dx.-^...dx,, 

JJJ       \n      71  —  1      71  — z  7i  —  r-\-l/ 


> 


...     CvX^   (JuJUn    ...     Ct/ll/j^ 


with  the  limitation 

x^  +  x^+  ...+x„  =  s (2). 

The  result  then  follows  by  the  aid  of  the  theorem  of  Lejeune 
Dirichlet :  we  shall  shew  that  this  result  is 

s  (1         1  1  ,11 

n  \n     71  —  1      71- z  7i  —  7'-\-l) 

35 


54i6  LAPLACE. 

For  let  us  suppose  that  instead  of  (2)  we  have  the  condition 
that  x^  +  x^+  ...  +  Xn  shall  lie  between  s  and  s  +  As.  Then  by  the 
theorem  to  which  we  have  just  referred  we  have 


m        1        2  n  [72  +  1 

and  \\\ dx^dx^,»,dxn=  ; 

Hence  by  division  we  obtain 


/// 


•  •  •  Xnn  CLX.,  (a/X„  •  •  •  UitL', 


jj^l^Oyj^U/tAy^    •••    ix/t*^„  f  A      Nn+1  W+1 


(5  +  AsY^"-  -  s' 


•  •  •  a*X/^  Ci/tO^  •  •  •  Cvt^Aj 
The  limit  of  this  expression  when  As  is  indefinitely  diminished 


///■ 


is  - .     Then  by  putting  for  m  in  succession  the  values  1,  2, . . .  r, 

we  obtain  the  result. 

Laplace  makes  the  following  application  of  the  result.  Sup- 
pose that  an  observed  event  must  have  proceeded  from  one  of 
n  causes  A,  B,  G, ...  ;  and  that  a  tribunal  has  to  judge  from  which 
of  the  causes  the  event  did  proceed. 

Let  each  individual  arrange  the  causes  in  what  he  considers 
the  order  of  probability,  beginning  with  the  least  probable.  Then 
to  the  r^^  cause  on  his  list  we  must  consider  that  he  assigns  the 
numerical  value 


1  fl         1  1 

n  In      n  —  1      n  —  2  n 


-r  +  1) 


The  sum  of  all  the  values  belonging  to  the  same  cause,  accord- 
ing to  the  arrangement  of  each  member  of  the  tribunal,  must  be 
taken ;  and  the  greatest  sum  will  indicate  in  the  judgment  of  the 
tribunal  the  most  probable  cause. 

990.  Another  example  is  also  given  by  Laplace,  which  we  will 
treat  independently.  Suppose  there  are  n  candidates  for  an  office, 
and  that  an  elector  arranges  them  in  order  of  merit ;  let  a  denote 
the  maximum  merit :  required  the  mean  value  of  the  merit  of  a 
candidate  whom  the  elector  places  r^^  on  his  list. 


LAPLACE.  547 

Let  ^1,  t^, ...  tn  denote  the  merits  of  the  candidates,  beginning 
with  the  most  meritorious.  The  problem  differs  from  that  just 
discussed,  because  there  is  now  no  condition  corresponding  to  the 
sum  of  the  ordinates  being  given  ;  the  elector  may  ascribe  any 
merits  to  the  candidates,  consistent  with  the  conditions  that  the 
merits  are  in  order,  none  being  greater  than  that  which  imme- 
diately precedes  it,  and  no  merit  being  greater  than  a. 

The  mean  value  of  the  merit  of  the  r*^  candidate  will  be 


///•• 


vv   CtL^    (^^n    .  •  .    Cvt', 


n 


•  •  •  etc,  ^^o  •  •  •  ^^n 


The  integrations  are  to  be  taken  subject  to  the  following  con- 
ditions :  the  variables  are  to  be  all  positive,  a  variable  ^^  is  never 
to  be  greater  than  the  preceding  variable  t^^,  and  no  variable  is  to 
be  greater  than  a.  Laplace's  account  of  the  conditions  is  not  in- 
telligible ;  and  he  states  the  result  of  the  integration  without 
explaining  how  it  is  obtained.     We  may  obtain  it  thus. 

X  Ut        t,i  =  X^,       fn_^  =  ^n  +  ^n-i?       ^n-2  ~  ^n-i  +  ^n-2>       '"  l         tneU     the 

above  expression  for  the  mean  value  becomes 

III    •  •  •    \p^n  ~r"  ^n—i    i    •  •  •  "i~  "^r)  ^«^i  CiOS^  ...  CIX^ 

with  the  condition  that  all  the  variables  must  be  positive,  and 
that  iCj  +  cCg  +  •••  +  ^n  i^^st  not  be  greater  than  a.  Then  we  may 
shew  in  the  manner  of  the  preceding  Ai'ticle  that  the  result  is 

{n  —  r-VV)  a 

Laplace  suggests,  in  accordance  with  this  result,  that  each 
elector  should  ascribe  the  number  n  to  the  candidate  whom  he 
thinks  the  best,  the  number  n—\  to  the  candidate  whom  he 
thinks  the  next,  and  so  on.  Then  the  candidate  should  be 
elected  who  has  the  greatest  sum  of  numbers.     Laplace  says, 

35—2 


548  LAPLACE. 

Ce  mode  d'election  serait  sans  doute  le  meilleur,  si  des  considerations 
6ti'angeres  au  merite  n'influaient  point  souvent  sur  le  clioix  des  elec- 
teurs,  meme  les  plus  honnetes,  et  ne  les  determinaient  point  a  placer 
aux  derniers  rangs,  les  candidats  les  plus  redoutables  a  celui  qu'ils  pre- 
ferent;  ce  qui  donne  un  grand  avantage  aux  candidats  d'un  merite 
mediocre.  Aussi  I'experience  I'a-t-elle  fait  abandonner  aux  etablissemens 
qui  I'avaient  adopte. 

It  would  be  interesting  to  know  where  this  mode  of  managing 
elections  bad  been  employed.  The  subject  had  been  considered  by 
Borda  and  Condorcet ;  see  Arts.  690,  719,  806. 

991.  Thus  we  close  our  account  of  the  second  Chapter  of 
Laplace's  work  which  we  began  in  Art.  970 ;  the  student  will  see 
that  comparatively  a  small  portion  of  this  Chapter  is  originally 
due  to  Laplace  himself. 

992.  Laplace's  Chapter  III.  is  entitled  Des  his  de  la  proha- 
hiliU,  qui  resultent  de  la  midtiplication  indefinie  des  evenemens :  it 
occupies  pages  275 — 303. 

993.  The  first  problem  is  that  which  constitutes  James  Ber- 
noulli's theorem.     We  will  reproduce  Laplace's  investigation. 

The  probability  of  the  hap]3ening  of  an  event  at  each  trial 
is  p;  required  the  probability  that  in  a  given  number  of  trials 
the  number  of  times  in  which  the  event  happens  will  lie  between 
certain  assigned  limits. 

Let  q  =  1  —  p  and  yu,  =  m  +  r^ ;  then  the  probability  that  the 
event  will  happen  m  times  and  fail  w  times  in  fi  trials  is  equal  to 
a  certain  term  in  the  expansion  of  (/;  +  q^,  namely 

\m\n      -^ 

Now  it  is  known  from  Algebra  that  if  m  and  n  vary  subject 
to   the   condition  that  m  +  n  is   constant,  the  greatest  value  of 

the   above   term   is  when   —   is   as   nearly  as   possible  equal  to 

-  ,  so  that  m  and  n  are  as  nearly  as  possible  equal  to  yup  and  y^q 
respectively.     We  say  as  nearly  as  possible,  because  jbLp  is  not 


LAPLACE.  549 

necessarily  an  integer,  while  m  is.  We  may  denote  the  value  of 
m  by  \xp  +  z,  where  z  is  some  proper  fraction,  positive  or  negative  ; 
and  then  n  =  ^q  —  z. 

The  r^^  term,  counting  onwards,  in  the  expansion  of  {p-\-q)'^ 

after  -^p^q-  is   ^      ,     p"-y^ 


\m  \n 


w 


We  shall  now  suppose  that  m  and  n  are  large  numbers,  and 
transform  the  last  expression  by  the  aid  of  Stirling's  Theorem  ; 
see  Arts.  333,  962.     We  have 


m  —  r  \/(27r)  [        12(/?i  — r) 


^      =  (?i  +  r)-"-'-^'  e"-''-  -7^  [1  -         ^ 


•  t  •  I    t 


n  +  r      ^  '  sl^'rr)  \        12  (?i  +  ?-) 

We  shall  transform  the  term  {in  —  r)*"""^"^.     Its  logarithm  is 

and  wri-^U-'"        '•'         '' 


We  shall  suppose  that  r^  does  not  surpass  //,  in  order  of  mag- 
nitude, and  we  shall  neo^lect  fractions  of  the  order  -  ;  we  shall 

thus  neglect  such  a  term  as  — ^,  because  vi  is  of  the  order  //-. 
Thus  we  have  approximately 

^r  -  m  -  2)  jlog  w  +  log  ^1  -  ^J  I 

/  1\  ,  r        r^         r^ 

\^  2/     °  ,  2«i     2??i      o»i 

and  then,  passing  from  the  logarithms  to  the  numbers, 

'-^  =  m'--'"-^  6*^2-  ( 1  +  -—  _  — -J  . 


(..  -  r)— ^  =  m--  e-2-^    1  +  ^^  -  ^.) 


550  LAPLACE. 


Similarly 

Thus  we  have  approximately 


"7r-,+ 


,-r+.^^«+r+|  JI9rrA  1  2ww  6m^       G^l' 


Now  suppose  that  the  values  of  m  and  w  are  those  which  we 
have  already  assigned  as  corresponding  to  the  greatest  term  of 
the  expansion  of  (i?  +  ^)^  then 

171  —  2  n  +  z 

thus  we  have  approximately 

m-r     n+r^  U  +  ^^     • 

t      ^  ^^        \        ran)  , 

Therefore  finally  we  have  approximately  for  the  r*^  term  after 
the  greatest 


tji^irmri)  \        mn  2mn  6m^      6n^ 

We  shall  obtain  the  approximate  value  of  the  r"^  term  before 
the  greatest  by  changing  the  sign  of  r  in  the  above  expression ; 
by  adding  the  values  of  the  two  terms  we  have 


2^/ll       .El 


i^i^irmn) 

If  we  take  the  sum  of  the  values  of  this  expression  from  r  =  0 
to  r  =  r,  we  obtain  approximately  the  sum  of  twice  the  greatest 
term  of  a  certain  binomial  expansion  together  with  the  r  terms 
which  precede  and  the  r  terms  which  follow  the  greatest  term ; 
subtract  the  greatest  term,  and  we  have  the  approximate  value  of 
the  sum  of  2^  +  1  terms  of  a  binomial  expansion  which  include 
the  greatest  term  as  their  middle  term. 

Now  by  Euler's  theorem,  given  in  Art.  33i, 


LAPLACE.  551 

2  J II        -Ell 

Here  y  =  ——-!-— -e  2""»    and  the  differential  coefficients  of  v 

with  respect  to  r  will  introduce  the  factor  -—- — ,  and  its  powers ; 

and  ^-—  is  of  the  order  —j-  at  most,  so  that  when  multiplied  by 

the  constant  factor  in  y  we  obtain  a  term  of  the  oraer  — .  Thus 
as  far  as  we  need  proceed, 

where  both  the  symbols  S  and  I  are  supposed  to  indicate  opera- 

1 

tions  commencing  with  «•  =  0,  and  ^  Y  denotes  the  gi'eatest  term 

1 

of  the  binomial  expansion,  that  is  the  value  oi  ^y  when  r  =  0. 

The  expression  ^y  denotes  as  usual  the  sum  of  the  values  of  y  up 
to  that  corresponding  to  r  —  1 ;  adding  the  value  of  y  correspond- 
ing to  r  we  obtain 

jydr-v^y  +  -^Y\ 

subtract  the  greatest  term  of  the  binomial,  and  thus  we  have 


I 


ydr-^^y. 


/y  kI  11, 

Put        T  =    ,.^      .    ;  thus  we  obtain  finally 


2       f      ...    7,  V/^ 


-2 


This  expression  therefore  is  the  apj^roximate  value  of  the  sum  of 
2r  + 1  terms  of  the  expansion  of  {p  +  qY,  these  terms  including 
the  greatest  term  as  their  middle  term.  In  the  theory  of  proba- 
bility the  expression  gives  the  probability  that  the  number  of 
times  in  which  the  event  will  happen  in  //,  trials  will  lie  between 
m  —  'T  and  m  +  r,  both  inclusive,  that  is  between 

T  \/(2mn)        T         ,       ,  r\/(2mn) 
^^^.^^_V^__and/x^  +  ^4--^^; 


552  LAPLACE. 

or,  in  other  words,  the  expression  gives  the  probability  that  the 
ratio  of  the  number  of  times  in  which  the  event  happens  to  the 
whole  number  of  trials  will  lie  between 

p^ ^^   ^.  and  p+  -+  -, — . 

If  fi  be  very  large  we  may  neglect  z  in  comparison  with  fip  or  fj.q ; 
and  then  onn  =  /Ji^pq  approximately,  so  that  we  obtain  the  following 
result ;  If  the  number  of  trials,  /jl,  be  very  large,  the  probability 
that  the  ratio  of  the  number  of  times  in  which  the  event  happens 
to  the  whole  number  of  trials  will  lie  between 


IS 


e-f^dt  +  ttJ^ ^e-^ 


\l'rr  Jo  Aj{27rfipq) 


994.  The  result  which  has  just  been  obtained  is  one  of  the 
most  important  in  the  whole  range  of  our  subject.  There  are  two 
points  to  be  noticed  with  respect  to  the  result. 

In  the  first  place,  it  is  obvious  that  supposing  r  to  be  constant 
we  may  by  sufficiently  increasing  jjl  render  the  limits 

as  close  as  we  please,  while  the  corresponding  probability  is  always 
greater  than  —i—       e  *'  dt 

2     C"^  _ 
In  the  second  place,  it  is  known  that  the  value  of  —r-  j     e^''  dt 

^  NTT  Jq 

approaches  very  near  to  unity  for  even  moderate  values  of  r. 
Tables  of  the  value  of  this  expression  will  be  found  in  the  works 
of  Professor  De  Morgan  cited  in  Arts.  268  and  485,  and  in  that  of 
Galloway  cited  in  Art.  753.  The  following  extract  will  sufficiently 
illustrate  the  rapid  approach  to  unity:  the  first  column  gives 
values  of  t,  and  the  second  column  the  corresponding  values  of  the 

expression  — —  I  e'^^  dt. 

YttJo 


LAPLACE. 

•5 

•5204999 

10 

•8427008 

1-5 

•9661052 

2  0 

•9953223 

2-5 

•9995930 

3-0 

•9999779 

553 


995.  With  respect  to  the  history  of  the  result  obtained  in 
Art.  994,  we  have  to  remark  that  James  Bernoulli  began  the 
investigation ;  then  Stirling  and  De  Moivre  carried  it  on  by  the  aid 
of  the  theorem  known  by  Stirling's  name ;  and  lastly,  the  theorem 
known  by  Euler's  name  gave  the  mode  of  expressing  the  finite 
summation  by  means  of  an  integral.  See  Arts.  123,  334,  335,  423. 
But  it  will  be  seen  that  practically  we  use  only  the  first  term 
of  the  series  given  in  Euler's  theorem,  in  fact  no  more  than 
amounts  to  evaluating  an  integral  by  a  rough  approximate  quadra- 
ture. Thus  the  result  given  by  Laplace  was  within  the  power  of 
mathematicians  as  soon  as  Stirling's  Theorem  had  been  published. 

Laplace,  in  his  introduction,  page  XLII,  speaking  of  James 
Bernoulli's  theorem  says, 

Ce  theoreme  indique  par  le  bon  sens,  6tait  difficile  a  demontrer  par 
I'Analyse.  Anssi  I'illustre  geometre  Jacques  Bernoulli  qui  s'en  est 
occup6  le  premier,  attachait-il  une  grande  importance  a  la  demonstra- 
tion qu'il  en  a  donnee.  Le  calcul  des  fonctions  generatrices,  applique 
a  cet  objet,  non-seulement  d^montre  avec  facilite  ce  theoreme ;  mais  de 
phis  il  donne  la  probabilite  que  le  rapport  des  evenemens  observes,  ne 
s'ecarte  que  dans  certaines  limites,  du  vrai  rapport  de  leurs  possibilites 
respectives. 

Laplace's  words  ascribe  to  the  theory  of  generating  functions 
the  merit  which  should  be  shared  between  the  theorems  known 
by  the  names  of  Stirling  and  Euler. 

We  may  remark  that  in  one  of  his  memoirs  Laplace  had  used 
a  certain  process  of  summation  not  connected  with  Euler's 
theorem  :  see  Art.  897. 


996.     Laplace  gives  the  following  example  of  the  result  ob- 
tained in  Art.  993. 


554i  LAPLACE. 

Suppose  that  the  probability  of  the  birth  of  a  boy  to  that  of 
the  birth  of  a  girl  be  as  18  to  17 :  required  the  probability  that 
in  14000  births  the  number  of  boys  will  fall  between  7363  and 
7037. 

Here 

i?=^,     q  =  ^,     m=7200,     n  =  6S00,     r=163: 

the  required  probability  is  '994303. 

The  details  of  the  calculation  will  be  found  in  Art.  74  of  the 
TJieory  of  Prohdbilities  in  the  EncyclopcEdia  MetropoUtana, 

997.  We  have  now  to  notice  a  certain  inverse  application 
which  Laplace  makes  of  James  Bernoulli's  theorem :  this  is  a 
point  of  considerable  importance  to  which  we  have  already  alluded 
in  Art.  125,  and  which  we  must  now  carefully  discuss. 

In  Art.  993  it  is  supposed  that  p  is  given,  and  we  find  the 
probability  that  the  ratio  of  the  number  of  times  in  which  the 
event  happens  to  the  whole  number  of  trials  will  lie  between 
assigned  limits.  Suppose  however  that  p  is  not  known  a  pi^oriy 
but  that  we  have  observed  the  event  to  happen  m  times  and  to 
fail  n  times  in  fi  trials.    Then  Laplace  assumes  that  the  expression 

given  in  Art.   993  will  be  the  probability  that  p—  —   lies   be- 

ft 

tween 

•         ^^/(2mn)  ^^^    ^  T>sJ{2mn)  ^ 

that  is,  Laplace  takes  for  this  probability  the  expression 

i-\\-i^di^  ,,y^  ,6-- (1). 

He  draws  an  inference  from  the  formula,  and  then  says,  on 
his  page  282, 

On  parvient  directement  ^  ces  resultats,  en  considerant  p  comme 
une  variable  qui  pent  s'etendre  depuis  zero  jusqu'a  I'unite,  et  en  deter- 
minant, d'apres  les  evenemens  observes,  la  probabilite  de  ses  diverses 
valeurs,  comme  on  le  verra  lorsqne  nous  traiterons  de  la  probabiUte  des 
causes,  deduite  des  evenemens  observes. 


LAPLACE.  555 

Accordingly  we  find  that  Laplace  does  in  effect  return  to  the 
subject ;  see  his  pages  363 — 366. 

In  the  formula  which  we  have  given  in  Art.  697,  suppose 
a=  0,  and  5  =  1;  then  if  the  event  has  been  observed  to  happen 
m  times  and  to  fail  n  times  out  oi  m  +  n  trials,  the  probability  that 
the  chance  at  a  single  trial  lies  between  a  and  yS  is 


J  a 


I  x'^il-xydx 
Jo 

-f                          m     T  \/(2m7i)       ^     m     T  \/(2mn) 
Let  a  = ,    p  =  — 1 — , 

where  fjL  =  m  +  n;  then  we  shall  shew,  by  using  Laplace's  method 
of  approximation,  that  the  probability  is  nearly 

2 


[V«V^ (2). 


VttJo 

For  with  the  notation  of  Art.  957  we  have  ?/  =  £c"'(l  -xY; 
the  value  of  x  which  makes  ^  a  maximum  is  found  from  the 
equation 

m         n 


=  0, 
SO  that  a  = 


m  +  n 
Then 

Y 


e = log 


^  {a-\-ey{i-a-ey 

~2  K+(l-a)^J  ~3  I?  ■"(13^1  +  - 
Thus,  approximately, 


2  _  1/      )  "t  It,         ]         6" 


2  ja"  '   (l-O  2»m 


556  LAPLACE. 

Therefore 


/ 


x'^il -xydx       Y     e-^'df 


jx'^il-xydx      yJ    e-t'dt 
=  -r-  I    e'^'dt=  -J--  I  V^  dt. 


"We  have  thus  two  results,  namely  (1)  and  (2)  :  the  former  is 
obtained  by  what  we  may  call  an  assumed  inversion  of  James 
Bernoulli's  theorem,  and  the  latter  we  may  say  depends  on  Bayes's 
theorem.  It  will  be  seen  that  the  two  results  are  not  quite  con- 
sistent ;  the  difference  is  not  practically  very  important,  but  it  is 
of  interest  theoretically. 

The  result  (2)  is  in  effect  given  by  Laplace  on  his  page  366 ; 
he  does  not  however  make  any  remark  on  the  difference  between 
this  result  and  that  which  we  find  on  his  page  282. 

On  page  209  of  his  RecJier cites... sur  la  Proh.  Poisson  gives  the 
result  (1)  which  he  obtains  by  the  same  assumption  as  Laplace.  But 
on  his  page  213  Poisson  gives  a  different  result,  for  he  finds  in  effect 
that  the  probability  that  the  chance  at  a  single  trial  lies  between 

m     V  \/{2mn)        ,  w      [v  -{■  dv)  \J{2'mn) 
— — -  and '. 

is  Vdv, 

where  F=-r-  e"^' ^7;:^ ^-e"^' (3). 

This  is  inconsistent  with  Poisson's  page  209 ;  for  if  we  take  the 
integral  j  Vdv  between  the  limits  —  t  and  +  t  for  v  it  reduces 

to  —  /   e~^  dt,  so  that  we  arrive  at  the  result  (2),  and  not  at  the 

result  (1).  It  is  curious  that  Poisson  makes  no  remark  on  the  dif- 
ference between  his  pages  209  and  213 ;  perhaps  he  regarded  his 
page  209  as  supplying  a  first  approximation,  and  his  page  213  as  a 
more  correct  investigation. 

Poisson's  result  (3)  is  deduced  by  him  in  his  RecheTches...sxir  la 
Proh.  from  the  same  kind  of  assumption  as  that  by  which  he  and 


LAPLACE.  557 

Laplace  arrived  at  the  result  (1)  ;  but  the  assumption  is  used  in 
such  a  way  as  to  diminish  very  decidedly  the  apprehension  of  any 
erroneous  consequences  :  the  assumption,  so  to  speak,  is  made  to 
extend  over  an  indefinitely  small  interval  instead  of  over  a  finite 
interval. 

Poisson  had  however  previously  considered  the  question  in  his 
Memoire  sur  la  proportion  des  naissances  des  deux  sexes;  this 
memoir  is  published  in  the  Memoires...de  VInstitut,  Yol.  ix,  1830  ; 
there  he  uses  Bayes's  theorem,  and  proceeds  as  we  have  done  in 
establishing  (2),  but  he  carries  the  approximation  further:  he 
arrives  at  the  result  (3).     See  page  271  of  the  memoir. 

Thus  the  result  (3)  is  demonstrable  in  two  ways,  namely,  by 
the  assumed  inversion  of  James  Bernoulli's  theorem,  and  by 
Bayes's  theorem.  As  Poisson  in  his  latest  discussion  of  the  ques- 
tion adopted  the  inversion  of  James  Bernoulli's  theorem,  we  may 
perhaps  infer  that  he  considered  the  amount  of  assumption  thus 
involved  to  be  no  greater  than  that  which  is  required  in  the  use  of 
Bayes's  theorem.     See  Art.  552. 

In  a  memoir  published  in  the  Cambridge  Philosophical  Trans- 
actions, Vol.  VI.  1837,  Professor  De  Morgan  drew  attention  to  the 
circumstance  that  Laplace  and  Poisson  had  arrived  at  the  result  (1) 
by  assuming  what  we  have  called  an  inversion  of  James  Bernoulli's 
theorem ;  and  he  gave  the  investigation  Avhich,  as  we  have  said, 
depends  on  Ba3^es's  theorem.  Professor  De  Morgan  however  over- 
looked the  fact  that  Laplace  had  also  implicitly  given  the  result 
(2),  and  that  Poisson  had  arrived  at  the  result  (3)  by  both 
methods.  It  will  be  found  on  examining  page  428  of  the  volume 
which  contains  Professor  De  Morgan's  memoir,  that  his  final 
result  amounts  to  changing  v'"^  into  v  in  the  second  term  of  the 
value  of  V  in  Poisson's  result  (3).  Poisson,  however,  is  correct ; 
the  disagreement  between  the  two  mathematicians  arises  from  the 
fact  that  the  approximations  to  the  values  of  fi  and  v  which  Pro- 
fessor De  Morgan  gives  towards  the  top  of  the  page  under  con- 
sideration are  not  carried  far  enough  for  the  object  he  has  in 
view. 

In  the  Treatise  on  Probability  by  Galloway,  which  is  con- 
tained in  the  Encyclopcedia  Britannica,  reference  is  expressly  made 
to  Professor  De  Morgan's  memoir,  without  any  qualifying  remark  ; 


558  LAPLACE. 

this  is  curious,  for  the  Treatise  may  be  described  as  an  abridge- 
ment of  Poisson's  Recherches . .  .SUV  la  Prob.,  and  Poisson  himself 
refers  to  his  memoir  of  1830  ;  so  that  it  might  have  been  expected 
that  some,  if  not  all,  of  our  conclusions  would  have  presented 
themselves  to  Galloway's  attention. 

998.  Laplace  discusses  in  his  pages  284 — 286  the  following 
problem.  An  urn  contains  a  large  number,  n,  of  balls,  some  white, 
and  the  rest  black;  at  each  drawing  a  ball  is  extracted  and  re- 
placed by  a  black  ball :  required  the  probability  that  after  r 
drawings  there  will  be  x  white  balls  in  the  urn. 

999.  The  remainder  of  the  Chapter,  forming  pages  287 — 303, 
is  devoted  to  investigations  arising  from  the  following  problem. 
There  are  two  urns,  A  and  B,  each  containing  n  balls,  some  white 
and  the  rest  black ;  there  are  on  the  whole  as  many  white  balls  as 
black  balls.  A  ball  is  drawn  out  from  each  urn  and  put  into  the 
other  urn;  and  this  operation  is  repeated  r  times.  Required  the 
probability  that  there  will  then  be  x  white  balls  in  the  urn  A. 

This  problem  is  formed  on  one  which  was  originally  given  by 
Daniel  Bernoulli;  see  Arts.  417,  587,  807,  921. 

Let  ^^. ,.  denote  the  required  probability;  then  Laplace  obtains 
the  following  equation: 

/ic  +  lV  ,  2x  A,      x\        ,  f^      x~ly 

This  equation  however  is  too  difficult  for  exact  solution,  and  so 
Laplace  mutilates  it  most  unsparingly.  He  supposes  n  to  be  very 
large,  and  he  says  that  we  have  then  approximately 

Q/Z^  If         1.  CL  Z  rg  ft 


LAPLACE.  559 

Let  X  =  — ^  ,  r  =  nr,  z^^^  =  Z7;  then  lie  saj^s  that  neglecting 
terms  of  the  order  —^  the  equation  becomes 

It  is  difficult  to  see  how  Laplace  establishes  this ;  for  if  we  adopt 
his  expressions  for  2;j.^i,r,  ^x-i,/?  and  z^^^^^-^,  the  equation  becomes 

dr  \       n)  \        n)  dp 

/,      11^     4      4\  d^U 

and  thus  the  error  seems  to  be  of  the  order  -,  or  even  laro^er,  since 

n  ° 

p^  may  be  as  great  as  n. 

1000.  Laplace  proceeds  to  integrate  his  approximate  equation 
by  the  aid  of  definite  integrals.  He  is  thus  led  to  investigate  some 
auxiliary  theorems  in  definite  integrals,  and  then  he  passes  on  to 
other  theorems  which  bear  an  analogy  to  those  which  occur  in 
connexion  with  what  are  called  Laplace  s  Functions,  We  will  give 
two  of  the  auxiliary  theorems,  demonstrating  them  in  a  way  which 
is  perhaps  simpler  than  Laplace's. 

To  shew  that,  if  i  is  a  positive  integer, 

/»    00        /•   00 

/      e-''-'-'{s-{-fiJ~^)'dsdtJL  =  0. 

*'  -00  "^  -00 

Transform  the  double  integral  by  putting 

s  =  r  cos  6,  fju  =  r^m.B\ 
we  thus  obtain 

[ *  ['"  e-"'  (cos  ^  6>  +  ^/^  sin  i  6)  r'^'  dr  dO. 

It  is   obvious  that  the  positive  and   negative  elements   in  this 
integral  balance  each  other,  so  that  the  result  is  zero. 

Again  to  shew  that,  if  t  and  q  are  positive  integers  and  q  less 
than  ij 


560  LAPLACE. 

»'  —00  ''  —00 

Transforming  as  before  we  obtain 

e-"'  (cos  10+  sT^l  sin  1 6)  sin^  6  r^^+^  Jr  ^6^. 

•'0      ''  0 

Now  sin^^  may  be  expressed  in  terms  of  sines  or  of  cosines 
of  multiples  of  6,  according  as  q  is  odd  or  even,  and  the  highest 
multiple  of  6  will  be  qO.  And  we  know  that  if  m  and  n  are 
unequal  integers  we  have 

/•27r 

I     sin  mO  cos  nO  dO  —  0, 


0 
r2rT 


I. 


cos  mO  cos  n6d6  =  0, 

0 

2n 


sin  md  sin  nd  dd  =  0 ; 


thus  the  required  result  is  obtained. 

Laplace  finally  takes  the  same  problem  as  Daniel  Bernoulli 
had  formerly  given ;  see  Art.  420.  Laplace  forms  the  differential 
equations,  supposing  any  number  of  vessels  ;  and  he  gives  without 
demonstration  the  solutions  of  these  differential  equations :  the 
demonstration  may  be  readily  obtained  by  the  modern  method 
of  separating  the  symbols  of  operation  and  quantity. 

1001.  Laplace's  Chapter  IV.  is  entitled,  De  la  prohahiUte  des 
erreurs  des  resultats  nioyens  d\in  grand  nomhre  d observations,  et 
des  resultats  moyens  les  plus  avantageux :  this  Chapter  occupies 
pages  304—348. 

This  Chapter  is  the  most  important  in  Laplace's  work,  and 
perhaps  the  most  difficult ;  it  contains  the  remarkable  theory 
which  is  called  the  method  of  least  squares.  Laplace  had  at  an 
early  period  turned  his  attention  to  the  subject  of  the  mean  to  be 
taken  of  the  results  of  observations ;  but  the  contents  of  the  pre- 
sent Chapter  occur  only  in  his  later  memoirs.  See  Arts.  874,  892, 
904,  917,  921. 

Laplace's  processes  in  this  Chapter  are  very  peculiar,  and  it  is 
scarcely  possible  to  understand  them  or  feel  any  confidence  in 


LAPLACE.  -561 

their  results  without  translating  them  into  more  usual  mathema- 
tical language.  It  has  been  remarked  by  R,.  Leslie  Ellis  that, 
"  It  must  be  admitted  that  there  are  few  mathematical  investiga- 
tions less  inviting  than  the  fourth  Chapter  of  the  Theorie  des 
ProhahiliUs,  which  is  that  in  which  the  method  of  least  squares 
is  proved."     Camhriclge  Phil.  Trans.  Vol.  viii.  page  212. 

In  the  Connaissance  des  Terns  for  1827  and  for  1832  there 
are  two  most  valuable  memoirs  by  Poisson  on  the  probability  of 
the  mean  results  of  observations.  These  memoirs  may  be  de- 
scribed as  a  commentary  on  Laplace's  fourth  Chapter.  It  would 
seem  from  some  words  which  Poisson  uses  at  the  beginning — 
j'ai  pense  que  les  remarques  que  j'ai  eu  I'occasion  de  faire  en 
1  etudiant, — that  his  memoirs  form  a  kind  of  translation,  Avhich  he 
made  for  his  own  satisfaction,  of  Laplace's  investigations.  Poisson 
embodied  a  large  part  of  his  memoirs  in  the  fourth  Chapter  of  his 
Recherches  sur  la  Proh.... 

We  shall  begin  our  account  of  Laplace's  fourth  Chapter  by 
giving  Poisson's  solution  of  a  very  general  problem,  as  we  shall 
then  be  able  to  render  our  analysis  of  Laplace's  processes  more 
intelligible.  But  at  the  same  time  it  must  be  remembered  that 
the  merit  is  due  almost  entirely  to  Laplace ;  although  his  pro- 
cesses are  obscure  and  repulsive,  yet  they  contain  all  that  is 
essential  in  the  theory :  Poisson  follows  closely  in  the  steps  of 
his  illustrious  guide,  but  renders  the  path  easier  and  safer  for 
future  travellers. 

1002.  Suppose  that  a  series  of  s  observations  is  made,  each 
of  which  is  liable  to  an  error  of  unknown  amount ;  let  these  errors 
be  denoted  by  e^,  e^,  ...  e^.  Let  E  denote  the  sum  of  these  errors, 
each  multiplied  by  an  assigned  constant,  say 

required  the  probability  that  E  will  lie  between  assigned  limits. 

Suppose  that  each  error  is  susceptible  of  various  values,  posi- 
tive or  negative,  and  that  these  values  are  all  multiples  of  a  given 
quantity  to.  These  values  will  be  assumed  to  lie  between  aw 
and  /S&),  both  inclusive ;  here  a  and  (3  will  be  positive  or  negative 
integers,  or  zero,   and  we  shall  suppose  that  a  is  algebraically 

36 


562  LAPLACE. 

greater  than  p,  so  that  a  — ^  is  positive.  The  chance  of  an  as- 
siofned  error  will  not  be  assumed  the  same  at  each  observation. 
If  71  be  any  integer  comprised  between  a  and  /3  we  shall  denote 
the  chance  of  an  error  71(0  at  the  first  observation  by  N^,  at  the 
second  observation  by  N^,  at  the  third  observation  by  N^,  and 
so  on.  Let  -ot  be  a  factor  such  that  all  the  products  -377^,  -5772 , 
'S773, ...  -5773  are  integers  ;  such  a  factor  can  always  be  found  either 
exactly  or  to  any  required  degree  of  approximation.     Let 

where  S  denotes  a  summation  with  respect  to  n  for  all  values 
from  P  to  a,  both  inclusive  ;  and  let 

J-  ^^  V1V2  *  •  *  ^s  * 

then  the  probability  that  'utE  will  be  exactly  equal  to  mo),  where 
m  is  a  given  integer,  is  the  coefficient  of  t^'^  in  the  development 
of  T  according  to  powers  of  t;  or,  which  is  the  same  thing,  the 
probability  is  equal  to  the  term  independent  of  t  in  the  develop- 
ment of  Tr^". 

For  f^  put  e^^^  and  denote  by  X  what  T  becomes ;  then  the 
required  probability  is  equal  to 

Let  X  and  fi  be  two  given  integers,  such  that  \  —  yit  is  positive ; 
then  the  probability  that  tjjE  will  lie  between  \co  and  /xo),  both 
inclusive,  may  be  derived  from  the  last  expression  by  putting  for 
m  in  succession  the  values  jx,  //-  +  !,  ^6  +  2,  ...  X,  and  adding  the  re- 
sults.    Since  the  sum  of  the  values  of  ^"'"^^"^  is 


7~i 

2sini6> 

2 


,-(x+i)0V-i  _  p-{i^-i)esl-i 


the  required  probability  is  equal  to 


sm  -  ^ 


we  shall  denote  this  probability  by  P. 


LAPLACE.  563 

Let  us  now  suppose  that  w  is  indefinitely  small,  and  that  X 
and  jx  are  infinite ;  and  let 


Xft)  =  (c  +  7;)  -ST,  11(0  =  (c  —  rj)  tar,   'urO  = 


cox. 


The  limits  of  the  integration  with  respect  to  x  will  be  +  00  . 
Also  we  have 

,^     ft)   ,        •    1/1     «^ 
av  =  —  ax,    sm  ^a  =  tt-  . 

Thus,  neglecting  ±  -  compared  with  X  and  /^,  we  obtain 

P=-        Xe-''^^-^  sin  77a'— (1). 

This  expression  gives  the  probability  that  'stE  will  lie  between 
(c  +  77)  t3-  and  (c  —  rj)  'ur,  that  is,  the  probability  that  E  will  lie 
between  c  +  rj  and  c  — 17. 

Since  we  suppose  co  indefinitely  small  we  consider  that  the 

error  at  each  observation  may  have  any  one  of  an  infinite  number 

of  values ;  the  chance  of  each  value  will  therefore  be  indefinitely 

small.     Let 

aft)  =  a,  /3ft)  =  h,  noa  —  z\ 


then 

ftayiUu 

=  ^^ 

YinflV-i  _gy{i 

ntax^~^--  gYiX^;  V-i 

Let 

iv;= 

= ^fi  (^) ; 

thus  Qi 

becomes 

r^(^) 

e-Zi^^^'^dz] 

and  for  X  in  (1)  we  must  put  the  new  form  which  we  thus  obtain 
for  the  product 

Assume         fi  (z)  cos  7"^  xz  dz  =  pi  cos  ?\, 

I    fi  (z)  sin  ji  xz  dz  =  pi  sin  r^ ; 

then  Qi-  pi^ 

Let  Y=  p^p^  p^  ...  p8> 

y  =  rj  +  r^  +  7-3  +  . . .  +  r, ; 

86—2 


564?  LAPLACE. 

then  X=F6^^. 

Substitute  in  (1)  and  we  obtain 

P=  —  j      F cos  (?/  —  ex)  sin  vx  — 
+  /     F  sin  (?/  —  ex)  sin  9;^  — . 

TT         J  -00  ^ 

The  elements  in  the  second  integral  occur  in  pairs  of  equal 
numerical  value  and  of  opposite  signs,  while  the  elements  in  the 
first  integral  occur  in  pairs  of  equal  numerical  value  and  of  the 
same  sign.     Thus 

2  f"                                     dx 
F  =  —j     Y  cos  (2/ —  ex)  sin  7]x —    (2). 

Since  each  error  is  supposed  to  lie  between  a  and  h  we  have 

I  fi  (^)  ^^  =  1- 

-^  b 

Hence  it  follows  that  pi  =  l  when  x  =  0;  and  we  shall  now 
shew  that  when  x  has  any  other  value  pi  is  less  than  unity. 

For  pl  =  \j  fi{z)  cos  jiXzdzY  +\      fi(z)smyiXzdz[ 
fa  ra 

that  is  Pi^  =      fi  (^)  COS  7^  xz  dz      fi  (z)  cos  7^ xz  dz' 

-lb  J  b 

ra  ra 

+  1   fi{z)^iriyixzdz  j   f  {z')  smji  xz'  dz 

ra    ra 

""]    J  fi{^)fi(^^')^osry,x(z'-z')dzdz; 
and  this  is  less  than 

that  is  less  than 

J  b  J  b 

that  is  less  than  unity. 


12 


LAPLACE. 


56o 


Up  to  this  point  the  investigation  has  been  exact:  we  shall 
now  proceed  to  approximate.  Suppose  5  to  be  a  very  large  num- 
ber; then  Y  is  the  product  of  a  very  large  number  of  factors,  each 
of  which  is  less  than  unity  except  when  x  =0.  We  may  infer  that 
Fwill  always  be  small  except  when  x  is  very  small;  and  we  shall 
find  an  a^Dproximate  value  of  Y  on  the  supposition  that  x  is  small. 


Let 


ra 

I    zfi  {z)  dz  =  Ici, 

J  b 

z'fi  {z)  dz  =  ki', 

J  b 
fa 

z^fi  (z)  dz  =  ki", 

J  b 

z\fi  {z)  dz  =  kl", 


Then  we  shall  have  in  converging  series 


.4..4  7   '" 


pi  cos  r^  =  1  — 


^^ikl      x^^ik, 


+ 


7       ^V-^/' 
pi  sm  Vi  =  X'^iki r^ f- 


Let 


2 


\3 


{k-  —  kl)  =  hi  ;  then  we  obtain 


Hence 
therefore 


pi=l  —x^^m^- , 

Ti  —  X'^^^i-V 

log /?i  =  -  a^V  V  + ; 

p.  =  e"^V/u2  approximately. 

Let  k'-  stand  for  ^<yihi,  and  I  for  ^Yi^'i,  each  summation  extend- 
ing for  the  values  of  i  from  1  to  5  inclusive.     Then  approximately 

Thus  (2)  becomes 

dx 


2  r        o  o  .  dx 

P  =  —       e"""^^  cos  ilx  —  cx)  sin  rjx  — 
7rj„  ^  ^         '      x 


(3). 


The  approximate  values  which  have  been  given  for  Y  and  2/ 
can  only  be  considered  to  be  near  the  truth  when  x  is  very  small ; 


566  LAPLACE. 

but  no  serious  error  will  arise  from  this  circumstance,  because 
the  true  value  of  Y  and  the  approximate  value  are  both  very- 
small  when  X  is  sensibly  different  from  zero.  We  may  put  (3)  in 
the  form 

F  =  —  j      <   I     cos  (Ix  —  CX  +  XV)  dv  j-  6""^'^'^  dx ; 

then  by  changing  the  order  of  integration,  and  using  a  result 
given  in  Art.  958,  we  obtain 

^=2^\f^^^' (^)- 

This  is  therefore  approximately  the  probability  that  E  will  lie 
between  c  —  rj  and  c-\-7j. 

It  is  necessary  to  shew  that  the  quantity  which  we  have 
denoted  by  k^  is  really  positive;  this  is  the  case  since  hi  is  really 
positive,  as  we  shall  now  shew.     From  the  definition  of  hi  in  con- 

junction  with  the  equation  I    fi  [z)  dz  =^  1,  we  have 

J  6 

U^  =  f "  z'f,  {z)  dz    ("f,  (z)  dz'  -  r  zf,  {z)  dz   ("z'f,  (z')  &■ 

J  h  J  b  J  b  J  b 


=  jj\z''-zz')f{z)f,{z')dzdz'. 


And  so  also 


2A?  =  JJ 1^  (/2  -  z^')f,  {z)fi  {£)  dz  dz'. 
Hence,  by  addition, 

^h^=n\z-z'ffi{z)f,{z')dzdz'. 

J  b  J  h 


Thus  ^hi  is  essentially  a  positive  quantity  which  cannot  be  zero, 
for  every  element  in  the  double  integral  is  positive. 

It  is  usual  to  call^  {z)  the  function  which  gives  the  facility  of 
error  at  the  i^'^  observation  ;  this  means  that  ^^  (2;)  dz  expresses  the 
chance  that  the  error  will  lie  between  z  and  z  +  dz. 

If  the  function  of  the  facility  of  error  be  the  same  at  every 


LAPLACE.  567 

observation  we  shall  denote  it  by  f{z) ;  and  then  dropping  those 
suffixes  which  are  no  longer  necessary,  we  have 

h  =  [ V(^)  ^^'    ^'  =  f"*^!/ (^)  ^-^^ 

J  b        ■  J  b 

Such  is  the  solution  which  we  have  borrowed  from  Poisson  ;  he 
presents  his  investigation  in  slightly  varying  forms  in  the  places 
to  which  we  have  referred :  we  have  not  adopted  any  form  ex- 
clusively but  have  made  a  combination  which  should  be  most  ser- 
viceable for  the  object  we  have  in  view,  namely,  to  indicate  the 
contents  of  Laplace's  fourth  Chapter.  Our  notation  does  not  quite 
agree  with  that  which  Poisson  has  employed  in  any  of  the  forms  of 
his  investigation ;  we  have,  for  example,  found  it  expedient  to 
interchange  Poisson's  a  and  h. 

We  may  make  two  remarks  before  leaving  Poisson's  problem. 

I.  We  have  supposed  that  the  error  at  each  observation  lies 
between  the  same  limits,  a  and  h ;  but  the  investigation  will  apply 
to  the  case  in  which  the  limits  of  error  are  different  for  different 
observations.  Suppose,  for  example,  it  is  known  at  the  first 
observation  that  the  error  must  lie  between  the  limits  a^  and  h^, 
which  are  within  the  limits  a  and  h.  Then  f^  {z)  will  be  a  function 
of  z  which  must  be  taken  to  vanish  for  all  values  of  z  between  h 
and  h^  and  between  a^  and  a. 

Thus  in  fact  it  is  only  necessary  to  suppose  that  a  and  h  are  so 
chosen,  that  no  error  at  any  observation  can  be  algebraically  greater 
than  a  or  less  than  h. 

II.  Poisson  shews  how  to  proceed  one  step  further  in  the  ap- 
proximation. We  took  y  —  Ix  \  we  have  more  closely  y—lx  —  l^ , 
where 

Hence,  approximately, 

cos  {y  —  ex)  =  cos  {Ix  —  ex)  +  l^x^  sin  {Ix  —  ex). 


568  LAPLACE. 

Therefore  (2)  becomes 

P=—  \    e        cosilx  —  ex)  sm  rix  — 

TTJo  ^ 

2L    r^     -/c2^2     .  \       2     •  7 

-\ \    e        sm  [Ix  —  ex)  x^  sm  7)X  ax. 

TT  J  0 

We  formerly  transformed  the  first  term  in  this  expression  of  P; 
it  is  sufficient  to  observe  that  the  second  term  may  be  derived 
from  the  first  by  differentiating  three  times  with  respect  to  /  and 
multiplying  by  l^ ;  so  that  a  transformation  may  be  obtained  for 
the  second  term  similar  to  that  for  the  first  term. 

1003.  Laplace  gives  separately  various  cases  of  the  general 
result  contained  in  the  preceding  Article.  We  will  now  take  his 
first  case. 

Let  7i  =  72=  •••  =78=  1-  Suppose  that  the  function  of  the 
facility  of  error  is  the  same  at  every  observation,  and  is  a  constant ; 
and  let  the  limits  of  error  be  +  a.     Then 

J  —a 

If  C  denote  the  constant  value  of  f{z)  we  have  then 

2a  (7=1. 

Here  Jc  =  0,  h'  =  -^—  =  —  ,   7^^  =  77 , 

Letc  =  0;  then  by  equation  (4)  of  the  preceding  Article  the 
probability  that  the  sum  of  the  errors  at  the  5  observations  will 
lie  between  —  77  and  77 

2a^[s'7r)  J  -ri  ^VM  Jo 

Let  —^^  =  f;  then  the  probability  that  the  sum  of  the  errors 
will  lie  between  —  ra  ^s  and  ra  V^ 

This  will  be  found  to  agree  with  Laplace's  page  805. 


LAPLACE.  569 

100-i.     We  take  Laplace's  next  case. 

Let  ry^  =  7^  =  •  •  •  =  7s  =  1-  ^^^  ^^^^  limits  of  error  he  ±a;  sup- 
pose that  the  function  of  the  facility  of  error  is  the  same  at  every 
observation,  and  that  positive  and  negative  errors  are  equally 
likely  :  thus  /  (—  x)  =f{x). 

Here  h  =  0,  A^=|^',   ^=0,   K'  =  ~h'. 

By  equation  (4)  of  Article  1002  the  probability  that  the  sum 
of  the  errors  at  the  s  observations  will  lie  between  —  rj  and  77 
is 

dv. 


2         [\-2sk' 


This  will  be  found  to  agree  with  Laplace's  page  808. 


'a  r  a 


We  have       k' =       z''f{z)dz=2      z'f{z)  dz, 


a  ra 


and  1  =        f[z)  dz=2      f{z)  dz ; 


-a 


hence  i^fiz)  always  decreases  as  z  increases  from  0  to  a  we  see,  as 

in  Art.  922,  that  h'  is  less  than  -^  . 

o 

1005.  Laplace  next  considers  the  probability  that  the  sum  of 
the  errors  in  a  large  number  of  observations  will  lie  between 
certain  limits,  the  sign  of  the  error  being  disregarded,  that  is  all 
errors  being  treated  as  positive ;  the  function  of  the  facility  of 
error  is  suj)posed  to  be  the  same  at  every  observation. 

Since  all  errors  are  treated  as  positive,  we  in  fact  take  nega- 
tive errors  to  be  impossible ;  we  must  therefore  jDut  5  =  0  in 
Poisson's  problem. 

Take  7^  =  ^3  =  •  ■  •  =  78  =  1.     Then 

Take  c  =  Z;  then,  by  equation  (-i)  of  Art.  1002,  the  probability 
that  the  sum  of  the  errors  will  lie  between  l—r]  and  l-\-7]  is 


570  LAPLACE. 


This  will  be  found  to  agree  with  Laplace's  page  311. 

For  an  example  suppose  that  the  function  of  the  facility  of 
error  is  a  constant,  say  C;  then  since 


[/(z)  dz  =  1, 

•^  0 


we  have  aC  =1. 

2  _2 

Thus  ^'  =  9 »    ^'  =  -o  '    ^*^  ~"  ^"^  =  19  • 

Therefore  the  probability  that  the  sum  of  the  errors  will  lie 

T  sa  ^  sa  . 

between  -^  —  v  and  -^  +  t;  is 


1006.  Laplace  next  investigates  the  probability  that  the  sum 
of  the  squares  of  the  errors  will  lie  between  assigned  limits,  sup- 
posing the  function  of  the  facility  of  error  to  be  the  same  at 
every  observation,  and  positive  and  negative  errors  equally  likely. 
In  order  to  give  the  result  we  must  first  generalise  Poisson's 
problem. 

Let  0i  {z)  denote  any  function  of  z :  required  the  probability 
that 

will  lie  between  the  limits  c  —  rj  and  c  +  77.  The  investigation 
will  differ  very  slightly  from  that  in  Art.  1002.  In  that  Article 
we  have 


J  b 


g7,a;W-i^^ 


in  the  present  case  the  exponent  of  e  instead  of  being  y^xzj—l, 

will  be   x(pi  {z)  J—  1.     The   required   probability    will   be   found 
to  be 

- — -r-      e      4"'     dv; 


LAPLACE.  571 

where  Z  =  S  I   (j>ii^)fi  (^)  ^^' 


'a 

b 

2 


and     2«='  =  2  j  ^  U  (2)|  f,  iz)  rf.t!  -  2 1  j^,  [z)f,  {z)  rf.j  . 

The  summations  extend  for  all  values  of  i  from  1  to  s,  both 
inclusive. 

It  is  not  necessary  that  </)i  {£)  should  be  restricted  to  denote 
the  same  function  of  z  for  all  the  values  of  i\  Poisson  however 
finds  it  sufiicient  for  his  purpose  to  allow  this  restriction. 

Suppose  now,  for  example,  that  cf)i{s)  =  z"  for  all  the  values 

of  ^;  and  let  the  function  of  the  facility  of  error  be  the  same 

at   every  observation.     Then,  taking  6  =  0,  as  in  the  preceding 

Article, 

ra 
1=  s  j   z^f  {z)  dzj 


'a  {  ra 


2/c'  =  5J  z'f{z)dz-sU   zy{z)dz)-. 

Take  c  =  l;  then  the  probability  that  the  sum  of  the  squares 
of  the  errors  will  lie  between  l  —  rj  and  I +  7]  is 


"~  dv. 


This  will  be  found  to  agree  with  Laplace's  page  312. 

1007.  Laplace  proceeds  in  his  pages  313 — 321  to  demonstrate 
the  advantage  of  the  method  of  least  squares  in  the  simplest  case, 
that  is  when  one  unknown  element  is  to  be  determined  from 
observations;  see  Art.  921.  This  leads  him  to  make  an  investi- 
gation similar  to  that  which  we  have  given  in  Art.  1002  from 
Poisson :  Laplace  however  assumes  that  the  function  of  the  facihty 
of  error  is  the  same  at  every  observation,  and  that  positive  and 
negative  errors  are  equally  likely,  and  thus  his  investigation  is 
less  general  than  Poisson's. 

Laplace  and  Poisson  agree  closely  in  their  application  of  the 
investigation  to  the  method  of  least  squares :  we  will  follow  the 
latter. 


572  LAPLACE. 

In  a  system  of  observations  the  quantity  given  by  tbe  observa- 
tion is  in  general  not  the  element  which  we  wish  to  determine, 
but  some  function  of  that  element.  We  suppose  that  we  already 
know  the  approximate  value  of  the  element,  and  that  the  required 
correction  is  so  small  that  we  may  neglect  its  square  and  higher 
powers.  Let  the  correction  be  represented  by  u ;  let  A^  be  the 
approximate  value  of  the  function  at  the  ^*^  observation,  and 
Ai  4-  uq^i  its  corrected  value.  Let  Bi  be  the  value  of  the  function 
given  by  observation,  e^  the  unknown  error  of  this  observation. 
Then  we  shall  have 

^i  +  6i  =  u4,  +  uq^. 

Put  8i  for  Bi  —  Ai,  so  that  Bi  is  the  excess  of  the  observed 
value  above  the  approximate  value  of  the  function ;  thus  we 
have 

ei  =  uqi  —  8i. 

A  similar  equation  will  be  furnished  by  each  of  the  s  observa- 
tions. All  the  quantities  of  which  qi  and  S^  are  the  types  will 
be  known,  and  all  those  of  which  e^  is  the  type  will  be  unknown. 
We  wish  to  obtain  from  the  system  of  equations  the  best  value 
of  u. 

Form  the  sum  of  all  such  equations  as  the  preceding,  each 
multiplied  by  a  factor  of  which  7^  is  the  type.     Thus  we  obtain 

tyiei  =  u^yiqi-t%Si (1). 

Then  by  equation  (4)  of  Art.  1002  the  probability  that  2)7^6^ 
will  lie  between  I—  t]  and  Z -f  ?;  is 


.,    _v^ 


^"^  dv, 


where  I  and  /c  have  the  values  assigned  in  that  Article. 

Put  27-5  =  ^ ;  thus  the  probability  that  Xyi€i  will  lie  between 
I  —  2tk  and  I  +  2tk  is 

~  I'e-^'dt (2). 


LAPLACE.  573 

If  in  (1)  we  put  I  for  X^e^  we  obtain 

and  there  is  therefore  the  probability  assigned  in   (2)  that  the 
error  in  the  value  of  u  will  lie  between 

2tk        ,    2tk 
and 


Supposing  then  that  r  remains  constant,  the  error  to  be  ap- 

/c 

prehended  will  be  least  when  -^^ is  least :   and  therefore  the 

factors  of  which  7^  is  the  type  must  be  taken  so  as  to  make 
this  expression  as  small  as  possible.  Put  for  k  its  value;  and 
then  the  expression  becomes 

We  then  make  this  expression  a  minimum  by  the  rules  of  the 
Differential  Calculus,  and  we  find  that  the  factors  must  be  deter- 
mined by  equations  of  which  the  type  is 

^'     hi  ' 
where  z^  is  a  coefficient  which  is  constant  for  all  the  factors. 
With  these  values  of  the  factors,  equation  (3)  becomes 

„  =  _jf  +  _5 (4); 

.hi      ^  hi 

and  the   limits  of  the  error  for   which  there  is  the  probability 
assigned  in  (2)  become 

If  the  function  of  the  facility  of  error  is  the  same  at  every 


574  LAPLACE. 

observation  the  quantities  of  which  hi  is  the  type  are  all  equal, 
and  so  are  those  of  which  Ic^  is  the  type.     Thus  (4)  becomes 

and  the  limits  of  error  become 

2t;i 


+ 


V(2^,^)  • 


If  we  suppose  also  that  positive  and  negative  errors  are 
equally  likely,  we  have  ^  =  0,  as  in  Art.  1004.  Thus  (5)  be- 
comes 


u  = 


(6). 


This  agrees  with  Laplace's  result. 

Laplace  also  presents  another  view  of  the  subject.  Suppose 
that  i/r  (x)  dx  represents  the  chance  that  an  error  will  lie  between 

X  and  x-\-dx\  then  I   x^jr  (x)  dx  may  be  called  the  mean  value 

of  the  positive  error  to  be  apprehended — la  valeur  moyenne  de 
Verreur  a  craindre  en  plus.  Laplace  compares  an  error  with  a 
loss  at  play,  and  multiplies  the  amount  of  the  error  by  the  chance 
of  its  happening,  in  the  same  way  as  we  multiply  a  gain  or  loss 
by  the  chance  of  its  happening  in  order  to  obtain  the  advantage 
or  disadvantage  of  a  player.  Laplace  then  examines  how  the 
mean  value  of  the  error  to  be  apprehended  may  be  made  as  small 
as  possible. 

In  equation  (4)  of  Art.  1002  put  c  —  rj',  and  suppose  positive 
and  negative  errors  equally  likely,  so  that  1=0:  then  the  proba- 
bility that  27^6^  will  lie  between  0  and  2?; 


Thus  the  probability  that  Syi€i  will  lie  between  0  and  t  is 

e~^'  dv, 


■j^  z*^  «2 


^k^JttJ^ 


LAPLACE.  575 

and  therefore  the  probabiHty  that  Xyid  will  lie  between  t  and 
T  ■]-  dr  is 

1 


2iK  sjlT 


e  ^^'dr. 


This   then  is   the   probability   that   the   error  in   u   will   lie 

between  =; •  and  -;=i ;   and    therefore    the   probability   that 

the  error  in  u  will  lie  between  x  and  x-\-dx  \^ 

P^e      ^-^     dx. 

This  then  is  what  we  denoted  above  by  i|r  (x)  dx ;    and  we 
obtain  therefore 


/.oo 

I    x^lr  (x)  dx  = 


which  is  least  when  r^ is  least.     This  leads  to  the  same  re- 

suit  as  before.  The  mean  value  of  the  positive  error  to  be  ap- 
prehended becomes  — — ^^-^;r  . 

Since  6i  =  uqi  —  8i  we  have 

If  we  were  to  find  u  from  the  condition  that  the  sum  of  the 
squares  of  the  errors  shall  be  as  small  as  possible,  we  should  obtain 
by  the  Differential  Calculus 

which  coincides  with  (6) ;  so  that  the  result  previously  obtained 
for  u  is  the  same  as  that  assigned  by  the  condition  of  making  the 
sum  of  the  squares  of  the  errors  as  small  as  possible.  It  will 
be  remembered  that  (6)  was  obtained  by  assuming  that  the 
function  of  the  facility  of  eri'or  is  the  same  at  every  observation, 
and  that  positive  and  negative  errors  are  equally  likely.  The 
result  in  (4)  does  not  involve  these  assumptions.     It  Tvdll  be  found 


576  LAPLACE. 

that  the  value  of  u  in  (4)   is  the  same  as  we  should  obtain  by 
seeking  the  minimum  value  of 

that  is  the  minimum  value  of 

1008.  It  is  very  important  to  observe  how  much  is  demon- 
strated with  respect  to  the  results  (4),  (5),  and  (6)  of  the  preceding 
Article.  There  is  nothing  to  assure  us  that  we  thus  obtain  the 
most  prohable  value  of  u,  in  the  strict  sense  of  these  words ;  neither 
Laplace  nor  Poisson  makes  such  an  assertion  :  they  speak  of  the 
method  as  the  most  advantageous  method,  as  the  method  luhich 
ought  to  he  'preferred. 

Let  us  compare  this  method  with  another  which  would  perhaps 
appear  the  most  natural,  namely  that  in  which  each  of  the  factors 
7j,  72'  •••  ^^  taken  equal  to  unity. 

In  the  preceding  Ai'ticle  we  arrived  at  the  following  result, 

Now  suppose  that  instead  of  giving  to  the  factors  7^,  73,  ...  the 
values  assigned  in  the  preceding  Article  we  take  each  of  them 
equal  to  unity ;  then  the  quantity  I  of  the  preceding  Article  be- 
comes SA^i,  that  is  sh  if  we  suppose  the  function  of  the  facility  of 
error  to  be  the  same  at  each  observation.  Hence  instead  of  (5)  we 
shall  have 

"=2^  +  % • W- 

Now  (5)  is  preferable  to  (7)  because  it  was  shewn  in  the  pre- 
ceding Article  that,  corresponding  to  a  given  probability,  the  limits 
of  the  error  in  (5)  are  less  than  the  limits  of  the  error  in  (7).     In 

2T7^ 
fact  the  limits  of  the  error  in  (5)  are  +    ..^    g,  ,  and  in  (7)  they 

are  +  — ^ — -  ;  and  the  result  that  the  former  limits  are  less  than 
Mi 


n^>7 


LAPLACE.  577 

the  latter  is  equivalent  to  the  known  algebraical  theorem  that 

{%q^^  is  less  than  s'Sql. 

Moreover  suppose  that  we  neglect  the  second  temi  on  the  right- 
hand  side  of  (5)  and  of  (7);  and  thus  arrive  at 

"=%/ (*5)'        "  =  2^, (^)' 

then  there  is  another  reason  why  (6)  is  preferable  to  (8)  ;  for,  by 
virtue  of  the  algebraical  theorem  just  quoted,  the  term  which  is 
neglected  in  arriving  at  (6),  is  less  than  the  term  which  is  neg- 
lected in  arriving  at  (8). 

» 

1009.     It  was  shewn  in  Art.  1007  that  there  is  the  probability 

(2)  that  the  limits  of  the  error  in  (6)  are  +    ,,^   ^,  .    This  involves 

^  "  V(S?i ) 
an  unknown  quantity  h.  Laplace  proposes  to  obtain  an  approxi- 
mate value  of  h  from  the  observations  themselves.  It  is  shewn  in 
Art.  1006  that  there  is  a  certain  probability  that  the  sum  of  the 
squares  of  the  errors  will  lie  between  l—y  and  l-\-rj.  Assume  I 
for  the  value  of  the  sum  of  the  squares  of  the  errors ;  thus 

t€,'  =  l  =  s[  \y  {2)  dz  =  2sh\ 

J  0 

Therefore  approximately 

72  _  ^_  ^  (uqi  -  ^iY . 

^  ~  2s  ~         2s 
and  with  the  value  of  u  from  (6)  of  Art.  1007,  we  obtain 

^^  2sXqr 

Thus  the  mean  value  of  the  positive  error  to  be  apprehended, 

7 

which  was  found  in  Art.  1007  to  be    .,   ^   ^.  ,  becomes 

tqNi^'-rrs) 

This  agrees  with  Laplace's  page  322. 

37 


578  LAPLACE. 

1010.  Laplace  now  proceeds  in  his  pages  822 — 329  to  the 
case  where  two  unknown  elements  are  to  be  determined  from  a 
large  number  of  observations ;  see  Art.  923.  Laplace  arrives  at 
the  conclusion  that  the  method  of  least  squares  is  advantageous 
because  the  results  which  it  gives  coincide  with  those  obtained  by 
making  the  mean  values  of  the  positive  errors  to  be  apprehended 
as  small  as  possible ;  the  investigation  is  very  laborious.  The 
same  assumptions  are  made  as  we  have  stated  at  the  end  of 
Art.  1007. 

Laplace  considers  that  he  has  thus  established  the  method  of 
least  squares  for  any  number  of  unknown  quantities,  for  he  asserts, 
on  his  page  327,  ...  i7  est  visible  que  V analyse  precedente 2')eut  seten- 
dre  a  un  nomhre  quelconque  d'elemens.  This  assertion,  however, 
seems  very  far  from  being  obvious. ' 

Poisson  has  not  considered  this  part  of  the  subject ;  on  account 
of  its  importance  I  shall  now  supply  investigations  by  which  the 
conclusions  obtained  in  Art.  1007  will  be  extended  to  the  case  of 
more  than  one  unknown  element.  I  shall  give,  as  in  Art.  1007, 
two  modes  of  arriving  at  the  result ;  Laplace  himself  omits  the 
first,  and  he  presents  the  second  in  a  form  extremely  different  from 
that  which  will  be  here  adopted.  In  drawing  up  the  next  Article 
I  have  obtained  great  assistance  from  the  memoir  by  R.  L.  Ellis 
cited  in  Art.  1001. 

1011.  Suppose  that  instead  of  one  element  to  be  determined 
by  the  aid  of  observations  we  have  any  number  of  elements  ;  sup- 
pose that  approximate  values  of  these  elements  are  known,  and 
that  we  have  to  find  the  small  correction  which  each  element 
requires.  Denote  these  corrections  by  x,  2/,  z,  ...  Then  the  general 
type  of  the  equations  furnished  by  the  aid  of  observations  will  be 

€i  =  aiX  +  hiy^CiZ+  ...  -qi ( 1 ) . 

Here  6^  is  unknown,  while  a^,  hi,  c^,  ...  q^  are  known.  Multiply 
(1)  by  7i,  and  then  form  the  sum  of  the  products  for  all  values  of 
^,  which  we  suppose  to  be  from  1  to  s,  both  inclusive.  And  let  the 
factors  7^,  ^y^,  ...  7^  be  taken  subject  to  the  conditions 

27A=0,     :^7A  =  0,  (2); 


LAPLACE.  579 

thus  we  obtain 

«,=|m+|M 3^_ 

Now  we  know  from  equation  (4)  of  Art.  1002  that  there  is  the 
probability 

irl}"^' W. 

that  Syi^i  will  lie  between  Z  —  2t/c  and  Z  +  ^tk,  where,  as  before, 
I  =  Syj^v     Put  Z  for  ^7^6^ ;  thus  (3)  becomes 

^=|Mt+  ^  ..(5); 

and  there  is  the  probability  (-i)  that  the  error  in  the  value  of  x, 
when  determined  by  (5),  will  Lie  between 

2T/g 

We  propose  then  to  make  ^ as  small  as  possible,  the  fac- 
tors being  taken  consistent  with  the  limitations  (2). 

Since  it  is  obvious  that  we  want  not  the  absolute  values  of 
the  factors  7^,  73,  73,  •••,  but  only  the  ratio  which  they  bear  to 
any  arbitrary  magnitude,  we  shall  not  really  change  the  problem 
if  we  impose  the  condition  '^'yia^  =  1.  Thus,  since  k^  =  ^j^h^,  we 
require  that  '^jiV  shall  be  a  minimum  consistent  with  the  con- 
ditions 

Xyiai  =  l,     tyihi=0,     ^7^  =  0 (6). 

Hence,  by  the  Differential  Calculus,  we  have 

tyjitdyi=0, 
^Gidyi  =  0, 
^hid^i  =  0, 

Therefore  by  the  use  of  arbitrary  multiphers  \  fi,  v,  ...  we 
obtain  a  set  of  s  equations  of  which  the  type  is 

ry.Jli^  =  \a.  -\-  fJ^hi  +  VCi  + ,....(/). 

37—2 


580 


LAPLACE. 


Let  ji  stand  for  y^ ;  then  from  (7)  we  can  deduce  the  follow- 
ing  system  of  equations  : 

1  =  Xtaiji  +  fJ^afiiji  +  vtafiji  +  . . .  ^ 

0  =  XtaihJi+  fMtk^ji+  v%hiCiji-\-  ...  \^ (8). 

0  =  Xtafiji  +  tJ&hiCiji  +  vtciji  +  . . . 


To  obtain  the  first  of  equations  (8)  we  multiply  (7)  by  aji, 
and  then  sum  for  all  values  of  i  paying  regard  to  (6)  ;  to  ob- 
tain the  second  of  equations  (8)  we  multiply  (7)  by  hji  and  sum  ; 
to  obtain  the  third  of  equations  (8)  we  multiply  (7)  by  Ciji  and 
sum ;  and  so  on.  The  number  of  equations  (8)  will  thus  be  the 
same  as  the  number  of  conditions  in  (6),  and  therefore  the  same 
as  the  number  of  arbitrary  multipliers  \  fju,  v,  ...  Thus  equations 
(8)  will  determine  X,  fi,  v,  ... ;  and  then  from  (5)  we  have 

x  =  tyiqi  +  l (9). 

We  shall  now  shew  how  this  value  of  x  may  practically 
be  best  calculated. 

Take  s  equations  of  which  the  type  is 

GiX  +  hi7/'  +  CiZ  + =qi  +  h. 

First  multiply  by  aji  and  sum  for  all  values  of  ^ ;  then  mul- 
tiply by  hji  and  sum  ;  then  multiply  by  cj]  and  sum  ;  and  so  on  : 
thus  we  obtain  the  following  system 


xta.^ji  +  ytafiiji  +  zt^a^Cij^  +  . . . 
xtapji  4-  ythlj\  +  zthiCiji^  +  ... 
x'tafiji  +  y^hiCiji  +  ztclji  +  . . . 


2  [qi  -H  h)  aji 

^  {qi  +  h)  hji 
2  {qt  +  h;)  c,j, 


r 


(10). 


Now  we  shall  shew  that  if  x  be  deduced  from  (10)  we  shall 
have  X  =  %%qi  +  I,  and  therefore  x  =  x. 

For  multiply  equations  (10)  in  order  by  X,  ^i,  v,  ...  and  add; 
then  by  (8) 


LAPLACE.  581 

x'  =  Xt  [qi  +  h)  aji  +  ^lt  (qi  +  k,)  hij\  +  vt  {qt  +  h)CiJi  + . . . 
=  2  (^.  +  h^ji  [Xtti -{■  lxhi  +  vCi+  ...] 
=^tyi{qi  +  k)  by  (7). 

The  advantage  of  using  equations  (10)  is  twofold ;  in  the 
first  place  we  determine  x,  and  thence  x,  by  a  systematic  process, 
and  in  the  next  place  we  see  that  the  equations  (10)  are  sym- 
metrical with  respect  to  x,  y ,  z,  ...  :  thus  if  we  had  proposed 
to  find  y,  or  z,  or  any  of  the  other  unknown  quantities  instead  of 
X,  we  should,  by  proceeding  in  the  same  manner  as  we  have 
already,  arrive  at  the  same  system  (10).  Hence  the  same  ad- 
vantage which  we  have  shewn  by  the  Theory  of  Probability  to 
belong  to  the  value  of  x  by  taking  it  equal  to  x,  will  belong 
to  the  value  of  y  by  taking  it  equal  to  y,  and  to  the  value  of  z 
by  taking  it  equal  to  z,  and  so  on.  In  fact  it  is  obvious 
that  if  we  had  begun  by  investigating  the  value  of  y  instead  of 
the  value  of  x  the  conditions  (6)  would  have  been  changed  in  such 
a  manner  as  to  leave  the  proportion  of  the  factors  y^,  %,  y^^,  "• 
unchanged ;  and  thus  we  might  have  anticipated  that  a  sym- 
tnetrical  system  of  equations  like  (10)  could  be  formed. 

We  have  thus  shewn  how  to  obtain  the  most  advantageous 
values  for  the  required  quantities  x,  y,  z,  ... 

Suppose  now  that  we  wished  to  find  the  values  of  x ,  y ,  z\  ... 
which  render  the  following  expression  a  minimum, 

'%f  [ciiX  +  hiy  +  CiZ  -i-  ...  —  $'i  -  ^if; 

it  will  be  found  that  we  arrive  at  the  equations  (10)  for  deter- 
mining X ,  y ,  z  ...  Hence  the  values  which  have  been  found  for 
X,  y,  z,  ...  give  a  minimum  value  to  the  following  expression 

^ji  {€i  —  kiY  that  is  Xf  ^^-T—j  ' 

If  h^  be  zero,  and  hi  constant,  for  all  values  of  t,  the  values  which 
have  been  found  for  x,  y,  z,...  render  the  sum  of  the  squares  of 
the  errors  a  minimum  :  as  in  Art.  1007  these  conditions  will  hold 
if  the  function  of  the  facility  of  error  is  the  same  at  every  ob- 
servation, and  positive  and  negative  errors  are  equally  likely. 


5S2  LAPLACE. 

Tims  we  have  completed  one  mode  of  arriving  at  the  result, 
and  we  shall  now  pass  on  to  the  other. 

If  we  proceed  as  in  the  latter  part  of  Art.  1007  we  shall 
find  that  the  probability  that  the  error  in  the  value  of  x,  when 
it  is  determined  by  (5),  lies  between  t  and  t-\-dt\^ 

^e  ^^dt (11). 

For  put  c  =  ?;  in  equation  (4)  of  Art.  1002.  Then  the  proba- 
bility that  SYi^i  will  lie  between  0  and  2?; 

ZksIit  J  ^r,  ZkisItt  J  0 

Thus  the  probability  that  S^ej  will  lie  between  t  and  r  +  dr  is 


1 


e     ^"^    dr, 


and  therefore  the  probability  that  ^Yi^i  will  lie  between  Z  +  t  and 
Z  +  T  +  dr  is 

1       _  j1 

This  is  therefore  the  probability  that  the  error  in  the  value  of 
X  when  determined  by  (5)  -will  lie  between 

T            1    T  +  dr 
;s—    and    -= . 

And  therefore  the  probability  that  the  error  in  the  value  of  x 
when  determined  by  (5)  will  lie  betv/een  t  and  t^dt\^  given  by  (11). 

The  mean  value  of  the  positive  error  to  be  apprehended  in  the 
value  of  X  will  be  obtained  by  multiplying  the  expression  in  (11) 
by  t  and  integrating  between  the  limits  0  and  oo  for  t.    Thus,  since 

^Ji^i  —  Ij  we  obtain  -^-  for  the  result :  and  therefore  if  we  pro- 

ceed  to  make  this  mean  error  as  small  as  possible  we  obtain  the 
same  values  as  before  for  the  factors  y,^,  %,  %,  -" 

It  will  be  interesting  to  develop  the  value  of  k.  Multiply 
equation  (7)  by  7^,  and  sum  for  all  values  of  z;  thus  by  (6)  we 
obtain 

/c^  =  X. 


LAPLACE.  583 

Suppose  then  we  have  two  unknown  quantities,  x  and  y ;  we 
find  from  (8) 


X  = 


and  the  mean  error  for  x  will  be     .    . 

The  mean  error  to  be  apprehended  for  y  may  be  deduced 
from  that  for  x  by  interchanging  a^  with  hi. 

If  there  are  three  unknown  quantities  we  may  deduce  the 
mean  error  from  that  which  has  just  been  given  in  the  case  of 
two  unknown  quantities  by  the  following  rule  : 

change  ^a^ji    into  'Za^^Ji ^o^'-     > 

{tkco\Y 


cUi 


change  l^h^^i    into  %KJi ^ 

change  Xajjiji  into  Zapij\  —  ^^  '  ^  ^T  '  ""^    . 

To  establish  this  rule  we  need  only  observe  that  if  we  have 
three  equations  (8)  we  may  begin  the  solution  of  them  by  ex- 
pressing V  from  the  last  equation  in  terms  of  X  and  //.,  and  sub- 
stituting in  the  first  and  second. 

By  a  similar  rule  we  can  deduce  the  mean  en'or  in  the  case  of 
four  unknown  quantities  from  that  in  the  case  of  three  unknown 
quantities  :  and  so  on. 

The  rule  is  given  by  Laplace  on  his  page  328,  without  any 
demonstration.  He  assumes  however  the  function  of  the  facility 
of  error  to  be  the  same  at  every  observation  so  that  j\  is  constant 
for  all  values  of  i\  and  he  takes,  as  in  Art.  1009, 


li!  = 


2s  ' 


1012.  Laplace  gives  on  his  pages  329—332  an  investigation 
which  approaches  more  nearly  in  generality  to  that  which  we 
have  sui3plied  in  Art.  1007  than  those  which  we  have  hitherto 
noticed  in  the  fourth  Chapter  of  the  Theorie  ...des  Proh. ;  see 
Art.  917.     Laplace  takes  the  same  function  of  the  faciUty  of  error 


58^  LAPLACE. 

at  every  observation,  but  he  does  not  assume  that  positive  and 
negative  errors  are  equally  likely,  or  have  equal  ranges. 

1013.  Laplace  says,  on  his  page  833,  that  hitherto  he  has 
been  considering  observations  not  yet  made ;  but  he  "will  now 
consider  observations  that  have  been  already  made. 

Suppose  that  observations  assign  values  a^,  a^,  ^g,  ...  to  an 
unknown  element ;  let  0  (z)  be  the  function  of  the  facility  of  an 
error  z,  the  function  being  supposed  the  same  at  every  observa- 
tion. Let  us  now  determine  the  probability  that  the  true  value 
of  the  element  is  x,  so  that  the  errors  are  a^  —  x,  a^  —  x,  a^  —  x,... 
at  the  various  observations. 

Let  P  =  (j)  {a^  —  x) .  (j>  (a^  —  x) .  <f)  {a^  —  x).  ... 

Then,  by  the  ordinary  principles  of  inverse  probability,  the  pro- 
ba^bility  that  the  true  value  lies  between  x  and  x  +  dx  is 

Pdx 


I 


Pdx 


the  integral  in  the  denominator  being  supposed  to  extend  over  all 
the  values  of  which  x  is  susceptible. 

Let  H  be  such  that,  with  the  proper  limits  of  integration, 

nlpdx^i. 


'I 


and  let  y  =  Hcj)  {a^  —  x)  .  ^  [a^  —  x)  .  cf)  {a^  —  x) .  . . . 

Laplace  conceives  that  we  draw  the  curve  of  which  the  ordi- 
nate is  7/  corresponding  to  the  abscissa  x.  He  says  that  the  value 
which  we  ought  to  take  as  the  mean  result  of  the  observations  is 
that  which  renders  the  mean  error  a  minimum,  every  error  being 
considered  positive.  He  shews  that  this  corresponds  to  the  point 
the  ordinate  of  which  bisects  the  area  of  the  curve  just  drawn ; 
that  is  the  mean  result  which  he  considers  the  best  is  such  that 
the  true  result  is  equally  likely  to  exceed  it  or  to  fall  short  of  it. 
See  Arts.  876,  918. 

Laplace  says,  on  his  page  335, 

Des  geometres  celebres  ont  pris  ponr  le  milieu  qu'il  faut  choisir, 
celui  qui  rend  le  resiiltat  observe,  le  plus  probable,  et  par  consequent 


LAPLACE.  585 

I'abscisse  qui  i^epond  k  la  plus  grande  ordonnee  de  la  courbe ;  mais  le 
milieu  que  nous  adoptons,  est  evidemment  iudique  par  la  theorie  des 
probabilites. 

This  extract  illustrates  a  remark  which  we  have  already  made 
in  Art.  1008,  namely  that  strictly  speaking  Laplace's  method  does 
not  profess  to  give  the  7nost  probable  result  but  one  which  he  con- 
siders the  most  advantageous. 

lOl-i.  Laplace  gives  an  investigation  in  his  pages  335 — 340 
which  amounts  to  solving  the  following  problem :  if  we  take  the 
average  of  the  results  furnished  by  observations  as  the  most  2:)ro- 
bable  result,  and  assume  that  positive  and  negative  errors  are 
equally  hkely  and  that  the  function  of  the  facility  of  error  is  the 
same  at  every  observation,  what  function  of  the  facihty  of  error  is 
implicitly  assumed  ? 

Let  the  function  of  the  facility  of  an  error  z  be  denoted  by 
e-'/'(z')^  which  involves  only  the  assumption  that  positive  and  nega- 
tive errors  are  equally  likely.  Hence  the  value  of  y  in  the  pre- 
ceding Article  becomes 

He-^, 

where         (7  =  '^{x  —  a^Y  +  y)r{x  —  a^Y  +  yjr  {x  —  a^Y  +  •  •  • 

To  obtain  the  most  probable  result  we  must  determine  x  so 
that  a  shall  be  a  minimum  ;  this  gives  the  equation 

{x  —  aj  yjr'  {x  —  ay  +  {x—  aj  i^'  (^  ~  ^2)^ 

+  {x  —  a^)  yjr'  {x-ay+  ...^  0. 

Now  let  us  assume  that  the  average  result  is  always  the  most 
probable  result ;  suppose  that  out  of  s  observations  ^  coincide  in 
giving  the  result  a^,  and  s  —  i  coincide  in  giving  the  result  a^ ;  the 
preceding  equation  becomes 

I  {x  —  aj  -v/r'  (x  —  a^  +  (s  —  i)  {x  —  a^  yfr'  (x  —  a^  =  0. 

The  average  value  in  this  case  is 

ia^  +  (g  —  i)  a^ 
s 

Substitute  this  value  of  x  in  the  equation,  and  we  obtain 
(s-{  V  {i  ^* 


586  LAPLACE. 

■ 

This  cannot  hold  for  all  values  of  -  and  a^  —  a^^  unless  i/r'  {z)  be 

s 

independent  of  z  ;  say  i/r'  (z)  =  c. 

Hence  '^  {z)  =  cz  +  c,  where  c  and  c  are  constants. 

Thus  the  function  of  the  facility  of  error  is  of  the  form  Ce~''^^ ; 
and  since  an  error  must  lie  between  —  oo  and  oo ,  we  have 

CJ     e-'''dz  =  l', 

J    —CO 

therefore  C  =  —r-  • 

The  result  given  by  the  method  of  least  squares,  in  the  case 

of  a  single  unknown  quantity,   is  the  same  as  that  obtained  by 

taking  the  average.     For  if  we  make  the  following  expression  a 

minimum 

{x-ay+  {x-a^y-\- ...  +  (x-a^y 

we  obtain 

a  +a  +...  +  as 

x  =  — . 

s 

Hence  the  assumption  in  the  preceding  investigation,  that 
the  average  of  the  results  furnished  by  observations  will  be  the 
most  probable  result,  is  equivalent  to  the  assumption  that  the 
method  of  least  squares  will  give  the  most  probable  result. 

1015.  Laplace  devotes  his  pages  310 — 312  to  shewing,  as  he 
says,  that  in  a  certain  case  the  method  of  least  squares  becomes 
necessary.  The  investigation  is  very  simj)le  when  divested  of  the 
cumbrous  unsymmetrical  form  in  which  Laplace  presents  it. 

Suppose  we  require  to  determine  an  element  from  an  assem- 
blage of  a  large  number  of  observations  of  various  kinds.  Let 
there  be  s^  observations  of  the  first  kind,  and  from  these  let  the 
value  a^  be  deduced  for  the  unknown  quantity;  let  there  be  s,^ 
observations  of  the  second  kind,  and  from  these  let  the  value  a^  be 
deduced  for  the  unknown  quantity ;  and  so  on. 

Take  x  to  represent  a  hypothetical  value  of  the  unknown  quan- 
tity. Assume  positive  and  negative  errors  to  be  equally  likely; 
then  by  Art.  1007  the  probability  that  the  error  of  the  result 
deduced  from  the  first  set  of  observations  will  lie  between  x  —  a^ 

Q 

and  x  +  dx  —  a.i^  ^  e-^i'^C^-  a)''  dx. 


LAPLACE.  587 

Here  SJ^  stands  for  ;  J.X., ,  and  tlie  value  of  B,  will  therefore 

depend  on  the  values  of  the  factors  y^^,  %, ...  which  we  employ;  for 
example  we  may  take  each  of  these  factors  equal  to  unity,  which 
amounts  to  adopting  the  average  of  the  results  of  observation ;  or 
we  may  take  for  these  factors  the  system  of  values  which  we  have 
called  the  most  advantageous  system  :  if  we  adopt  the  latter  we 

Similarly  the  probability  that  the  error  of  the  result  deduced 
from  the  second  set  of  observations  will  lie  between  x  —  a^  and 

And  so  on  for  the  other  sets  of  observations. 

Hence  we  shall  find,  in  the  manner  of  Art.  1013,  that  the  pro- 
bability that  X  is  the  true  value  of  the  unknown  quantity  is  pro- 
portional to 


x-\-dx-a^  is  -^  e-^2Mx-a2)Vic, 


e-^ 


where       (t  =  ^^  (x-a^^  +  ^^  (x- a^""  +  I3^\x-  a^'  +  ... 

Now   determine   x   so   that    this   probability    shall   have    its 
greatest  value ;  a  must  be  a  minimum,  and  we  find  that 

^  /3>^  +  ff /g,  +  /g>.,  +  . . . 

We  may  say  then  that  Laplace  obtains  this  result  by  deducing 
a  value  of  the  unknown  quantity  from  each  set  of  observations, 
and  then  seeking  for  the  most  p7'ohahle  inference.  If  a^,  a^,  a^,  ... 
are  determined  by  the  most  advantageous  method,  this  result  is 
similar  in  form  to  that  which  is  given  in  Art.  1007,  if  we  suppose 
that  positive  and  negative  errors  are  equally  likely,  and  that  one 
function  of  facility  of  error  applies  to  the  first  set  of  observations, 
another  function  to  the  second  set,  and  so  on.     For  the  numerator 

of  the  value  of  x  just  given  corresponds  with  the  S-y^,  and  the 


h^ 


denominator  with  the  Sti>  of  Art.  1007. 


588  LAPLACE. 

1016.  Laplace  gives  some  remarks  on  his  pages  343 — 348 
relative  to  another  method  of  treating  errors,  namely,  that  which 
consists  in  making  the  sum  of  the  2n^^  powers  of  the  errors  a 
minimum,  n  being  supposed  indefinitely  great.  He  explains  this 
method  for  the  case  of  one  unknown  quantity,  and  he  refers  to  the 
Mecanique  Celeste,  Livre  ill.  for  the  case  in  which  there  is  more 
than  one  unknown  quantity.  The  section  intended  of  Livre  IIL 
must  be  the  39th,  in  which  Laplace  gives  some  rules  as  in 
the  present  place,  but  without  connecting  his  rules  with  the  con- 
sideration of  infinite  powers  of  the  errors.  Another  method  is  given 
in  the  next  section  of  the  Mecanique  Celeste  which  Dr  Bowditch 
in  a  note  on  the  passage  ascribes  to  Boscovich  :  Laplace  takes  up 
this  method  in  the  second  Supplement  to  the  Theorie...des  Proh., 
where  he  calls  it  the  method  of  situation. 

1017.  Laplace  gives  on  his  pages  346 — 348  some  account  of 
the  history  of  the  methods  of  treating  the  results  of  observations. 
Cotes  first  proposed  a  rule  for  the  case  in  which  a  single  element 
was  to  be  determined.     His  rule  amounts  to  taking 

7i  =  72  =  "-  =7s  =  l 
in  Art.  1007,  so  that 

S3, 

Laplace  says  that  the  rule  was  however  not  employed  by  mathe- 
maticians until  Euler  employed  it  in  his  first  memoir  on  Jupiter 
and  Saturn,  and  Mayer  in  his  investigations  on  the  libration  of 
the  moon.  Legendre  suggested  the  method  of  least  squares  as 
convenient  when  any  number  of  unknown  quantities  had  to  be 
found  ;  Gauss  had  however  previously  used  this  method  himself 
and  communicated  it  to  astronomers.  Gauss  was  also  the  first 
who  endeavoured  to  justify  the  method  by  the  Theory  of  Proba- 
bihty. 

We  have  seen  that  Daniel  Bernoulli,  Euler,  and  Lagrange  had 
studied  the  subject :  see  Arts.  424,  427,  5oQ.  Lambert  and  Bos- 
covich also  suggested  rules  on  the  subject ;  see  the  article  Milieu  of 
the  Encyclopedie  Methodique  and  Dr  Bowditch's  translation  of  the 
Mecanique  Celeste,  Yol.  ii.  pages  434,  435. 


LAPLACE.  589 

The  titles  of  some  other  memoirs  on  the  subject  of  least  squares 
will  be  found  at  the  end  of  the  Treatise  on  Probability  in  the 
Encyclopcedia  Britamiica ;  we  would  also  refer  the  student  to  the 
work  by  the  Astronomer  Eoyal  On  the  A  Igebraical  and  Numerical 
Theory  of  Errors  of  Observations  and  the  combination  of  Observa- 
tions. 

1018.  Laplace's  fifth  Chapter  is  entitled  Application  du  Calcid 
des  Probabilites,  a  la  recherche  des  phenomenes  et  de  leurs  caicses : 
it  occupies  pages  31;9 — 3G2. 

The  example  with  which  Laplace  commences  will  give  a  good 
idea  of  the  object  of  this  Chapter.  Suppose  that  observations 
were  made  on  400  days  throughout  which  the  height  of  the 
barometer  did  not  vary  4  millimetres ;  and  that  the  sum  of  the 
heights  at  nine  in  the  morning  exceeded  the  sum  of  the  heights 
at  four  in  the  afternoon  by  400  millimetres,  giving  an  average 
excess  of  one  millimetre  for  each  day :  required  to  estimate  the 
probability  that  this  excess  is  due  to  a  constant  cause. 

We  must  examine  what  is  the  probability  of  the  result  on 
the  supposition  that  it  is  not  due  to  any  constant  cause,  but 
arises  from  accidental  perturbations  and  from  errors  of  ob- 
servation. 

By  the  method  of  Art.  1004,  supposing  that  it  is  equally  pro- 
bable that  the  daily  algebraical  excess  of  the  morning  result  over 
the  afternoon  result  will  be  positive  or  negative,  the  probability 
that  the  sum  of  s  excesses  will  exceed  the  positive  quantity  c 


,00  V 


i2 


2sk'  ^^ 


^^{2k's7^)  J, 

=  —r-  I    e~^' dt,     where  t  =    ,,^  ,,,  . 
VttJt  f^{zsk) 


Hence  the  probability  that  the  sum  will  be  algebraically  less 
than  c  is 

1  r 


590  LAPLACE. 


a^ 


Now,  as  in  Art.  1004,  we  may  take  -^  as  the  greatest  value 

c  \/3 
of  1c  y  so  that  the  least  value  of  r  is  — 77^ ;  also  a  =  4,  c  =  400, 

a  \l{^s)  '  ' 

5\/  3 
s  =  400  :  thus  the  least  value  of  r  is  —j^  ,  that  is  \/(S^'5). 

1  r 

Hence  1 j-  \    e~^'^dt  is  found  to  be  very  nearly  equal  to 

unity.  We  may  therefore  regard  it  as  nearly  certain  that  the 
sum  of  the  excesses  would  fall  below  400  if  there  were  no  constant 
cause :  that  is  we  have  a  very  high  probability  for  the  existence  of 
a  constant  cause. 

1019.  Laplace  states  that  in  like  manner  he  had  been  led 
by  the  theory  of  probabilities  to  recognise  the  existence  of  con- 
stant causes  of  various  results  in  physical  astronomy  obtained  by 
observation ;  and  then  he  had  proceeded  to  verify  the  existence 
of  these  constant  causes  by  mathematical  investigations.  The 
remarks  on  this  subject  are  given  more  fully  in  the  Introduction, 
pages  LVII — LXX  ;  see  Art.  938. 

1020.  Laplace  on  his  pages  359 — 362  solves  BufFon's  problem, 
which  we  have  explained  in  Art.  650. 

Suppose  that  there  is  one  set  of  parallel  lines ;  let  a  be  the 
distance  of  two  consecutive  straight  lines  of  the  system,  and  2r 
the  length  of  the  rod :    then  the   chance  that  the  rod  will  fall 

across  aline  is  — .     Hence,  bv  Art.  993,  if  the  rod  be  thrown 

down  a  very  large  number  of  times  we  may  be  certain  that  the 
ratio  of  the  number  of  times  in  which   the   rod   crosses  a  line 

to  the  whole  number  of  trials  will  be  very  nearly  —  :  we  might 

therefore  determine  by  experiment  an  approximate  value  of  tt. 

8r 
Laplace  adds . . .  et  il  est  facile  de  voir  que  le  rapport  —  qui, 

pour  un  nombre  donn^  de  projections,  rend  I'erreur  a  craindre  la 
plus  petite,  est  I'unite...  Laplace  seems  to  have  proceeded  thus. 
Suppose^  the  chance  of  the  event  in  one  trial;  then,  by  Art.  993, 


I^APLACE.  591 

the  probability  that  in  fjb  trials  the  number  of  times  in  which  the 
event  happens  will  lie  between 

jpiJb  —  T  sl'lfii?  (1  —p)  and  p>iJi  +  T  V2/x^j>  (1-2^) 

2     f"^ 
is  approximately  -j-       e'^^  dt 

Hence  to  make  the  limits  as  close  as  possible  we  must  have 
p  [^-p)  as  small  as  possible,  and  thus  p  =  -^.  This,  we  say,  ap- 
pears to  have  been  Laplace's  process.  It  is  however  wrong ;  for 
p  (1  — ^;)  is  a  maximum  and  not  a  minimum  when  p=-^.     More- 

over  we  have  not  to  make  r  V2yC6p  (1  -  p)  as  small  as  possible, 
but  the  ratio  of  this  expression  to  p\x.     Hence  we  have  to  make 

sj p  n  _  27)  \ 

—^—^ ^  as  small  as  possible ;  that  is  we  must  make 1   as 

small  as  possible :  therefore  p  must  be  as  great  as  possible.     In 

the  present  case  ^  =  —  ;   we  must  therefore  make  this  as  great 

as  j)ossible :  now  in  the  solution  of  the  problem  2r  is  assumed 
to  be  not  greater  than  a,  and  therefore  we  take  2r  =  a  as  the 
most  favourable  length  of  the  rod. 

Laplace's  error  is  pointed  out   by   Professor   De   Morgan  in 

Art.    172    of  the    Theory   of  Prohahilities   in   the   Encyclopcedia 

Metro])olitana.     The   most  curious  point  however  has  I  believe 

hitherto  been  unnoticed,  namely,  that  Laplace  had   the  correct 

result  in  his  first  edition,  where  he  says  ...et  il  est  facile  de  voir 

2r        . 
que    le    rapport    —  qui,  pour  un  nombre  donne  de  projections, 

rend  I'erreur  a  craindre  la  plus  petite,  est  I'unite  . . .  The  original 
leaf  was  cancelled,  and  a  new  leaf  inserted  in  the  second  and  third 
editions,  thus  causing  a  change  from  truth  to  error.     See  Art.  932. 

Laplace  solves  the  second  part  of  Buffon's  problem  correctly, 
in  which  Buffon  himself  had  failed;  Lai^lace's  solution  is  much 
less  simple  than  that  which  we  have  given  in  Art.  650. 


592-  LAPLACE. 

1021.  Laplace's  sixth  Chapter  is  entitled  De  la  prohahilite  des 
causes  et  des  Mnemens  futurs,  tiree  des  evenemens  observes:  it 
occupies  pages  363 — 401. 

The  subject  of  this  Chapter  had  engaged  Laplace's  attention 
from  an  early  period,  and  to  him  we  must  principally  ascribe 
the  merit  of  the  important  extension  thus  given  to  the  Theory  of 
Probability,  due  honour  being  at  the  same  time  reserved  for  his 
predecessor  Bayes.     See  Arts.  851,  868,  870,  903,  909. 

Let  X  denote  the  chance,  supposed  unknown,  of  a  certain 
simple  event ;  let  y  denote  the  chance  of  a  certain  compound 
event  depending  in  an  assigned  manner  on  this  simple  event : 
then  y  will  be  a  known  function  of  x.  Suppose  that  this  com- 
pound event  has  been  observed ;  then  the  probability  that  the 
chance  of  the  simple  event  lies  between  a  and  ^  is 

I    y  dx 


\    y  dx 

Jo  ' 

This  is  the  main  formula  of  the  present  Chapter:  Laplace 
applies  it  to  examples,  and  in  so  doing  he  evaluates  the  integrals 
by  his  method  of  approximation. 

In  like  manner  if  the  compound  event  depends  on  two  inde- 
pendent simple  events,  the  probability  that  the  chance  of  one  lies 
between  a  and  fi  and  the  chance  of  the  other  between  a!  and  ^'  is 

y  dx  dx 


ny  dx  dx 
0 

1022.  The  examples  in  the  present  Chapter  of  Laplace's  work 
exhibit  in  a  striking  way  the  advantage  of  his  method  of  approxi- 
mation ;  but  as  they  present  no  novelty  nor  difficulty  of  principle 
we  do  not  consider  it  necessary  to  reproduce  any  of  them  in  detail. 

1023.  Laplace  makes  a  remark  on  his  page  366  which  may 
deserve  a  brief  examination.     He  says  that  if  we  have  to  take  the 

integral  I  e-^'  dt  between  the  limits  —  r  and  r   we  may  for  an  ap- 


LAPLACE.  593 

proximation  take  the  integral  between  the  limits  0  and 


2    /* 

and  double  the  result :  he  says  this  amounts  to  neglecting  the 
square  of  t'^  —  rl  We  may  put  the  matter  in  the  following  form  : 
suppose  that  a  and  h  are  positive,  and  we  require  x  such  that^ 


/. 


"'e-''dt+{\-^dt  =  2\  ""e-^'  dt 


Suppose  a  less  than  h  ;  then  in  fact  we  require  that 


a  J  X 

'a'  + 1' 


Laplace,  in  effect,  tells  us  that  we  should  take  x  = 


2   ; 

as  an  approximation.     He  gives  no  reason  however,  and  the  more 

natural  approximation  would  be  to  take  x  =  ^  (a +  5),  and  this  is 

certainly  a  better  approximation  than  his.     For  since  the  function 
e~^^    decreases   as    t   increases,   the   true  value   of  x  is   less  than 

1  .  ,  .        .       .  1 

^  (a +  5),  while  Laplace's  approximation  is  greater  than  ^  (a  +  V). 

1024.  Laplace  discusses  on  his  pages  869 — 376  a  problem  re- 
lating to  play  ;  see  Art.  868.  A  and  B  play  a  certain  number  of 
matches ;  to  gain  a  match  a  player  must  win  two  games  out  of 
three ;  having  given  that  A  has  gained  i  matches  out  of  a  large 
number  n,  determine  the  probability  that  -4's  skill  lies  within  as- 
signed limits.  If  a  player  wins  the  first  and  second  games  of  a 
match  the  third  is  not  played,  being  unnecessary ;  hence  if  n 
matches  have  been  played  the  number  of  games  must  lie  between 
2/i  and  3?i :  Laplace  investigates  the  most  probable  number  of 
games. 

1025.  Laplace  discusses  in  his  pages  377 — 380  the  problem 
which  we  have  enunciated  in  Art.  896.  The  required  proba- 
bility is 

x'i^-xYdx 


i: 


[  x^ii-xydx 

■^  0 

where  p  and  q  have  the  values  derived  from  observations  during 

38 


594  LAPLACE. 

40  years ;  these  values  are  given  in  Art.  902.  Laplace  finds  that 
the  probability  is  approximately 

1  -  -0030761 

where  /a  is  a  very  large  number,  its  logarithm  being  greater  than 
72.  Thus  Laplace  concludes  that  the  probability  is  at  least  equal 
to  that  of  the  best  attested  facts  in  history. 

With  respect  to  a  formula  which  occurs  in  Laplace's  solution 
see  Art.  767.  With  respect  to  an  anomaly  observed  at  Vitteaux 
see  Arts.  768,  769. 

1026.  Laplace  discusses  in  his  pages  381 — 384  the  problem 
which  we  have  noticed  in  Art.  902. 

He  offers  a  suggestion  to  account  for  the  observed  fact  that  the 
ratio  of  the  number  of  births  of  boys  to  girls  is  larger  at  London 
than  at  Paris. 

1027.  Laplace  then  considers  the  probability  of  the  results 
founded  on  tables  of  mortality  :  he  supposes  that  if  we  had  observa- 
tions of  the  extent  of  life  of  an  infinite  number  of  infants  the  tables 
would  be  perfect,  and  he  estimates  the  probability  that  the  tables 
formed  from  a  finite  number  of  infants  will  deviate  to  an  assigned 
extent  from  the  theoretically  perfect  tables.  We  shall  hereafter  in 
Art.  1036  discuss  a  problem  like  that  which  Laplace  here  considers. 

1028.  A  result  which  Laplace  indicates  on  his  page  390  sug- 
gests a  general  theorem  in  Definite  Integrals,  which  we  will  here 
demonstrate. 

Let  u^  = 

let  e~^^  be  integrated  with  respect  to  each  of  the  n  —  1  variables 
z^,  z^,  ...  Zn_^,  between  the  limits  —  oo  and  oo  :  then  the  result 
will  be 

n-l 


Cf|i*2  •  •  •  ^'n_i^7i 


e-Y^^„', 


where         -^  =  — ^^  +  ~^  +  —H-fj}^  +  . . .  +  -i-^ — 2—^ 


LAPLACE.  595 

Let  us  consider  first  the  integration  with  respect  to  z^ ;  we  have 

=  (a^+a%')  (z ^2'^i^2    Y  ,      2   2        <^xX' 


2       2      2 

a.  a„  ^. 


a^  +  a^  ^1 


where        ^  =  2;, 2"^— ^~2^~2  • 

1     a/  +  a^b^ 


The  limits  of  ^  will  be  —  x  and  00  ;  integrate  with  respect  to 
t :  thus  we  remove  z^  entirely,  and  obtain  the  factor 


and  instead  of  the  first  two  terms  in  w^  we  have  the  single  term 

ttj  ci^  z^ 

We  integrate  next  with  respect  to  z^ ;  thus  we  shall  remove 
^2  entirely,  and  introduce  the  factor 


and  instead  of  the  first  three  terms  in  ic^  we  shall  have  the  single 
term 

2      2      2„  2      /»         /v  2      2  ■N  -1 

"'1  ^'2  ^3  ^3      j  ^1  S  I     ^  2X  2I 

<  +  <^"'      l<  +  <^l'  "^  ^3  ^2  I       • 

Thus  we  have  now  on  the  whole  the  factor 
where  -rs  =  — 2  +  -^  +  ^   ^  ' 


-  «3  «2  «i 


2      ? 


and  the  first  three  terms  in  u^  are  replaced  by  the  single  term  \\^. 

38—2 


596  LAPLACE. 

We  integrate  next  with  respect  to  z^ ;  thus  we  shall  remove  z^ 
entirely,  and  introduce  the  factor 

that  IS,   ^- 


LLiJlT 
^  1  1  h 

where  -^  =  —2  + 


2 


3 


and  the  first  four  terms  in  u^  are  replaced  by  the  single  term 

\^a  2   2 
^2  ,  '  2^7  2  J  that  is,  by  /x'2;/. 

A     +  «4  t>3 

By  proceeding  in  this  way  it  is  obvious  that  we  shall  arrive  at 
the  assigned  result. 

1029.  Laplace  devotes  his  pages  391 — 394^  to  a  problem 
which  we  have  indicated  in  Art.  911.  The  problem  resembles 
that  which  we  have  noticed  in  Art.  1027,  and  the  mode  of  solution 
will  be  illustrated  hereafter  in  Art.  1036. 

The  problems  which  Laplace  considers  in  his  pages  385 — 394 
relate  to  the  probabilities  of  future  events ;  and  thus  these  pages 
are  strangely  out  of  their  proper  place  :  they  should  h.2iYQ  followed 
the  discussion  which  we  are  about  to  analyse  in  our  next  Article, 
and  which  begins  thus,  Considerons  maintenant  la  prohahilite  des 
ivenemens  futurs,  tir^e  des  evenemens  observes. 

1030.  Laplace  considers  in  his  pages  394 — 396  the  impor- 
tant subject  of  the  probability  of  future  events  deduced  from 
observed  events :  see  Ai'ts.  870,  903,  909. 

Retaining  the  notation  of  Art.  1021,  suppose  that  z,  which  is 
a  known  function  of  x,  represents  the  chance  of  some  compound 
future  event  depending  on  the  simple  event  of  which  x  represents 
the  chance :  then  the  whole  probability,  P,  of  this  future  event 
will  be  given  by 

I  yzdx 


0  _ 


j  y  dx 

J  0 

Laplace  then  suggests  approximations  for  the  integrals  in  the 


LAPLACE.  597 

above  expression.  We  will  reproduce  the  substance  of  his  remarks. 
In  Art.  957  we  have 

^2  =  log  r-log^(a+(9) 

=  log  Y-  log  !</,  (a)  +  ecp'  (a)  +  |  f  [a)  +  ..  j 

~      2    (/)(«)  '^"'' 
for   Y=  (j)  (a),  and  ^'  (a)  =  0,  by  hypothesis. 
Thus  approximately 

Hence  if  i/  vanishes  when  a;  =  0  and  when  x=l,  we  have 
approximately 


^/(- 


Similarly  if  we  suppose  that  yz  is  a  maximum  when  x  =  a, 
and  that  then  yz  =  Y'Z',  we  have 


j/'^'^^         //    d'Y'Z'\' 


Suppose  that  0  is  a  function  of  3/,  say  s  =  (j)  (3/),  then  3/2  is 
a  maximum  when  ?/  is  a  maximum,  so  that  a  =a\  and  since 

--—  =  0,  we  find  that 
da 

d'Y'Z'      ( .  ,_   .  ,..,,_)  ^^F 


J^  =  {<^(r)  +  rf(r)| 


Hence  we  have  approximately 


P= 


■<^(n 


a/{ 


1031.  Laplace  discusses  on  his  pages  397 — 401  the  following 
problem.  It  has  been  observed  during  a  certain  number  of  years 
at  Paris  that  more  boys  than  girls  are  annually  baptised :  deter- 
mine the  probability  that  this  superiority  will  hold  during  a  cen- 
tury.    See  Art.  897. 


598  LAPLACE. 

Let  ^  be  the  observed  number  of  baptisms  of  boys  during  a 
certain  number  of  years,  q^  the  observed  number  of  baptisms  of 
girls,  2w  the  annual  number  of  baptisms.  Let  x  represent  the 
chance  that  an  infant  about  to  be  born  and  baptised  will  be  a 
boy. 

Let  (a?  +  1  —  xf"  be  expanded  in  a  series 

x^^  +  ^^nx'^-'  (1  -  ^)  +  ^"^  ^f '  ~  ^^  x''^''  {I -xy +...', 

then  the  sum  of  the  first  n  terms  of  this  series  will  represent  the 
probability  that  in  a  year  the  number  of  baptisms  of  boys  will 
predominate. 

Denote  this  sum  by  ^;  then  f^  will  be  the  probability  that 
the  superiority  will  be  maintained  during  i  years. 

Hence  we  put  x^  {1  —  xY  for  y  and  f  ^  for  z  in  the  formula  of 
the  preceding  Article,  and  obtain 


P  = 


I   x""  [1  -  x)"  t,' dx 
1x^(1-  xy  dx 


Laplace  applies  his  method  of  approximation  with  great  success 
to  evaluate  the  integrals.  He  uses  the  larger  values  of  p  and  q^ 
given  in  Art.  902  ;  and  he  finds  that  P=  '782  approximately. 

1032.  Laplace's  seventh  Chapter  is  entitled  De  V influence  des 
ineg allies  inconnues  qui  peuvent  exister  entre  des  chances  que  Von 
suppose  parfaitement  egales :  it  occupies  pages  402 — 407. 

The  subject  of  this  Chapter  engaged  the  attention  of  Laplace 
at  an  early  period ;  see  Arts.  877,  881,  891.     Suppose  the  chance 

of  throwing  a  head  with  a  coin  is  either  — ^ —  or  — ^ — ,  but  it  is 

as  likely  to  be  one  as  the  other.     Then  the  chance  of  throwing 
n  heads  in  succession  will  be 

,       .      1   r        72  (n  —  1)    2  _  71  (w  —  1)  (^  —  2)  (7^  —  8)    4 
that  IS,  ^  jl  +     ^^   ^  ^a^-f— ^  ^  I  ^     ^  ^ ^a*+... 


LAPLACE.  599 

Thus  there  is  an  advantage  in  undertaking  to  throw  n  heads 
in  succession  beyond  what  there  would  be  if  the  coin  were  per- 
fectly symmetrical. 

Laplace  shews  how  we  may  diminish  the  influence  of  the  want 
of  symmetry  in  a  coin. 

Let  there  be  two  coins  A  and  B',  let  the  chances  of  head 
and  tail  in  ^  be  ^  and  q  respectively,  and  in  B  let  them  be  p 
and  q  respectively :  and  let  us  determine  the  probability  that  in 
n  throws  the  two  coins  shall  always  exhibit  the  same  faces. 

The  chance  required  is  {pp  +  qqY. 

Suppose  that 

1 +a  1-a 

,     1  +  a'         ,      1-a' 

then  {pp  +  qqf  =  ^.  (1  +  ««  )"  • 

But  as  we  do  not  know  to  which  faces  the  want  of  S3nTimetry 
is  favourable,  the  preceding  expression  might  also  be  »^  (1  —  aa')" 

by  interchanging  the   forms  of  p  and  q  or  of  p    and  q.     Thus 
the  true  value  will  be 

iji(l  +  aar+i(l-«a')''}, 

that  is 

1    f        n{n-l)        ,     n{n-\)[n-^){n-Z)    ,„         { 
2-„|l+      j_2      aa   + g  aa  +...^. 

It  is  obvious  that  this  expression  is  nearer  to  —  than  that 

which  was  found  for  the  probability  of  securing   n   heads  in  7i 
throws  with  a  single  coin. 

1033.  Laplace  gives  again  the  result  which  we  have  noticed 
in  Art.  891.  Suppose  p  to  denote  ^'s  skill,  and  q  to  denote  B's 
skill ;  let  A  have  originally  a  counters  and  B  have  originally  b 
counters.     Then  A's  chance  of  ruining  B  is 


600  LAPLACE. 

Laplace  puts  for  p  in  succession  ^  (1  +  a)   and  ^  (1  —  a),  and 
takes  half  the  sum.     Thus  he  obtains  for  ^'s  chance 

1  {(1  +  g)"-  (1  -^■)"1  [il  +  oy+{l-of] 

2  (1  +  a)"+'  -  (1  -  af^"" 

Laplace  says  that  it  is  easy  to  see  that,  supposing  a  less  than 

h,   this   expression  is  always   greater   than  ,  ,    which   is  its 

limit  when  a  =  0.  This  is  the  same  statement  as  is  made  in 
Art.  891,  but  the  proof  will  be  more  easy,  because  the  trans- 
formation there  adopted  is  not  reproduced. 

Put  -z. =  X, 

1  —  a 


and  'ii  =         .  „+6 


We  have  to  shew  that  u  continually  increases  as  x  increases 
from  1  to  00  ,  supposing  that  a  is  less  than  h.    It  will  be  found  that 

1  du  _  ax"  [x^  -l)-ha^  [x"^  -  1) 
udx"  x[x''-l){x''  +  l){x''^-l)' 

We  shall  shew  that  this  expression  cannot  be  negative. 
We  have  to  shew  that 


h  a 

cannot  be  negative.  • 

This  expression  vanishes  when  a;  =  1,  and  its  differential  coeffi- 
cient is  {o^~^  —  x°-~^)  (1  — ic~"~*),  which  is  positive  if  x  lie  between 
1  and  oc  ;  therefore  the  expression  is  positive  if  x  lie  between 
1  and  00 . 

Laplace  says  that  if  the  players  agree  to  double,  triple, ... 
their  respective  original  numbers  of  counters  the  advantage  of  A 
will  continually  increase.  This  may  be  easily  shewn.  For  change 
a  into  lea  and  h  into  hh :  we  have  then  to  shew  that 

(a^"  -  1)  (a^^  +  1) 


LAPLACE.  601 

continually  increases  with  h.     Let  x^  —y\  then  we  have  to  shew 

that 

(/-1)(/+1) 

2/"+^  - 1 

continually  increases  as  y  increases  from  unity :  and  this  is  what 
we  have  already  shewn. 

1034.  Laplace's  eighth  Chapter  is  entitled  Des  durees  moyennes 
de  la  vie,  des  mariages  et  des  associations  quelcoiiques:  it  occupies 
pages  408 — 418. 

Suppose  we  have  found  from  the  tables  of  mortality  the 
mean  duration  of  the  life  of  n  infants,  where  n  is  a  very  large 
number.  Laplace  proposes  to  investigate  the  probability  that  the 
deviation  of  this  result  from  what  may  be  considered  to  be  the 
true  result  will  lie  within  assigned  limits :  by  the  true  result  is 
meant  the  result  which  would  be  obtained  if  n  were  infinite. 
Laplace's  analysis  is  of  the  same  kind  as  that  in  his  fourth  Chapter. 

1035.  Laplace  then  examines  the  effect  which  would  be 
produced  on  the  laws  of  mortality  if  a  particular  disease  were  ex- 
tinguished, as  for  example  the  small-pox.  Laplace's  investigation 
resembles  that  of  Daniel  Bernoulli,  as  modified  by  D'Alembert : 
see  Arts.  402,  405,  483. 

"We  will  give  Laplace's  result.  In  Art.  402,  we  have  arrived 
at  the  equation 

dx     n     mn ' 

fc  .         1  1 

where  o'  =  - .     Put  i  for  -  ,  and  r  for  —  :  and  let  i  and  r  not  be 
^      s  n  m 

assumed  constant.     Thus  we  have 

da 

-y-  =iq  —  ir. 

ax       ^ 

Let  V  denote  e"/^^;  thus 

-gv  =  -{rv; 

therefore  qv—  constant  —  Itrv  dx. 


602  LAPLACE. 

The  constant  is  unity,  if  we  suppose  the  lower  limit  of  the 
integral  to  be  0,  for  q  and  v  are  each  unity  when  a;  =  0 ;  thus 


gy  =  1—  I  irv  dx. 


The  differential  equation  obtained  in  Art.  405  becomes  when 
expressed  in  our  present  notation 

1  dz      1  d^  _  ir  _         irv 

z  dx      ^  dx      q      -        r .      ,    ' 

1  —  \irv  dx 

therefore,  by  integration, 

z  _    constant 

1—1  irv  dx 
As  before  the  constant  is  unity ;  thus 


z  = 


1  —  I  irx)  dx 

This  result  agrees  with  that  on  Laplace's  page  414. 

Laplace  intimates  that  this  would  be  an  advantageous  formula 
if  i  and  r  were  constants ;  but  as  these  quantities  may  vary,  he 
prefers  another  formula  which  he  had  previously  investigated,  and 
which  we  have  given  from  D'Alembert  in  Art.  483.  He  says  that 
by  using  the  data  furnished  by  observation,  it  appears  that  the 
extinction  of  the  small-pox  would  increase  by  three  years  the 
mean  duration  of  life,  provided  this  duration  be  not  affected  by 
a  diminution  of  food  owing  to  the  increase  of  population. 

1036.  Laplace  discusses  in  his  pages  415 — 418  the  problem 
of  the  mean  duration  of  marriages  which  had  been  originally 
started  by  Daniel  Bernoulli ;  see  Arts.  412,  790. 

Laplace's  investigation  is  very  obscure :  we  will  examine  various 
ways  in  which  the  problem  may  be  treated. 

Suppose  yu,  men  aged  A  years  to  marry  yu,  women  of  the  same 
age,  /I,  being  a  large  number :  determine  the  probability  that  at 
the  end  of  T  years  there  Avill  remain  an  assigned  number  of  un- 


LAPLACE.  603 

broken  couples.  The  law  of  mortality  is  assumed  to  be  the  same 
for  men  as  for  women ;  and  we  suppose  that  the  tables  shew  that 
out  of  7)1^  +  71^  persons  aged  A  years,  77i^  were  alive  at  the  end  of 
T  years,  tti^  and  7ij^  being  large. 

One  mode  of  solving  the  proposed  problem  would  be  as  follows. 

Take —  as  the  chance  that  a  specified  individual  will  be  alive 

771^  4-  Wj 

/     m      \^ 
at  the  end  of  T  years ;  then —     will  be  the  chance  that  a 

specified  pair  will  be  alive,  and  we  shall  denote  this  by  2?.  There- 
fore the  chance  that  at  the  end  of  T  years  there  will  be  v  un- 
broken couples,  out  of  the  original  jii  couples,  is 

la 
— — p^'Cl-pY-". 

fjb—  V  \v 


This  is  rioforous  on  the  assumption  that  ^ —  is  exactly  the 

^  ^  711^  +  71^  -^ 

chance  that  a  specified  individual  will  be  alive  at  the  end  of 
T  years :  the  assumption  is  analogous  to  what  we  have  called  an 
inverse  use  of  James  Bernoulli's  theorem ;  see  Art.  997. 

Or  we  may  solve  the  problem  according  to  the  usual  principles 
of  inverse  probability  as  given  by  Bayes  and  Laplace.  Let  x 
denote  the  chance,  supposed  unknown,  that  an  individual  aged 
A  years  will  be  alive  at  the  end  of  T  years.  We  have  the  ob- 
served event  recorded  in  the  tables  of  mortality,  that  out  of  m^-\-n^ 
persons  aged  A  years,  m^  were  alive  at  the  end  of  J' years.  Hence 
the  quantity  denoted  by  y  in  Art.  1030  is 


m^  \7i^ 


and  the  quantity  denoted  by  z  is 


{xy{i-xy-^; 


therefore       P  = 


fjL—  v\v 

,  f  V^  (1  -  xY'  (x'Y  (1  -  x'y-^  dx 


604?  LAPLACE. 

Laplace  however  adopts  neither  of  the  above  methods ;  but 
forms  a  mixture  of  them.  His  process  may  be  described  thus : 
Take  the  first  form  of  solution,  but  use  Bayes's  theorem  to  deter- 


m,     \^ 


mine  the  value  of  ^,  instead  of  putting^  equal  to  i 

We  will  complete  the  second  solution.  The  next  step  ought 
to  consist  in  evaluating  strictly  the  integrals  which  occur  in  the 
expression  for  P;  we  shall  however  be  content  with  some  rough 
approximations  which  are  about  equivalent  to  those  which  Laplace 
himself  adopts. 

Assume,  in  accordance  with  Art.  993,  that 


^ —  (x'Y  (1  -  xy--  =  - , 

where  r  is  supposed  to  be  not  large,  and  to  be  such  that  nearly 

V  =  x^fjb  —  r,    fjb  —  V  =  {1  —  x^)  [JL -^  r. 

Thus      p= ^o^2^/;fa-^-'0 . 

I  x'^^ii -xy^dx 

J  0 

Then,  as  in  Arts.  957,  997,  we  put 

x^^  (1  -  xY^  =  Ye-^\ 

x  =  a+  ~-^^l  ,  nearly, 
where  a  = 


And  finally  we  have  approximately 


r2 


e    ifia^il-a-i) 


^2'7rfid'  (1  -  a'O  ■ 
Then  we  have  to  effect  a  s-ummation  for  different  values  of  r, 


LAPLACE.  60o 

like  that  given  in  Art.  993.     The  result  is  that  there  is  approxi- 
mately the  probability 

that  the  number  of  unbroken  couples  will  lie  between 

fia'-T\f2fia'{l-d')  and  /J^d" +  t  ^/2y.a'' {1- a!'). 

This  substantially  agrees  with  Laplace,  observing  that  in  the 
third  line  of  his  page  418  the  equation  ought  to  be  simplified  by 
the  consideration  that  p'  has  been  assumed  very  great ;  so  that 
the  equation  becomes 


271  f  (1  -  (j^')  ' 

See  Art.  148  of  the  Theory  of  Prohahilities  in  the  Encyclopcedia 
Metropolitana. 

There  is  still  another  way  in  which  the  problem  may  be  solved. 
We  may  take  it  as  a  result  of  observation  that  out  of  fi^  man-iages 
of  persons  aged  A  years  there  remained  v^  unbroken  couples  at 
the  end  of  T  years,  and  we  require  the  consequent  probability 
that  out  of  fji  marriages  now  contracted  between  persons  aged 
A  years  v  unbroken  couples  will  remain  at  the  end  of  T  years. 
Then  as  in  Art.  1030  we  obtain 


P  = 


\1  \f: — ^         I  ic"!  (1  -  a?)'*i-»'i  dx 

J  0 


The  result  will  be  like  that  which  we  have  found  by  the 

second  method,  having  —  instead  of  al     Practically  -^  may  be 

nearly  equal  to  a^,  but  tliey  must  not  be  confounded  in  theory, 
being  obtained  from  ^Ufferent  data.  The  last  mode  is  simpler  in 
theory  than  the  second,  but  it  assumes  that  we  have  from  observa- 
tion data  which  bear  more  immediately  on  the  problem. 

1037.  Laplace's  ninth  Chapter  is  entitled  Des  benefices  depen- 
dans  de  la  prohabiliU  des  Svenemens  futiirs:  it  occupies  pages 
419—481. 


606  LAPLACE. 

Suppose  that  a  large  number  of  trials,  s,  is  to  be  made,  and 
that  at  each  trial  one  of  two  cases  will  happen ;  suppose  that  in 
one  case  a  certain  sum  of  money  is  to  be  received,  and  in  the 
other  case  a  certain  other  sum :  determine  the  expectation. 

Laplace  applies  an  analysis  of  the  same  kind  as  in  his  fourth 
Chapter ;  we  shall  deduce  the  required  result  from  the  investiga- 
tion in  Art.  1002.  We  supposed  in  Art.  1002  that  all  values  of 
a  certain  variable  z  were  possible,  and  that  fi  {£)  denoted  the 
chance  at  the  ^"^  trial  that  the  value  would  lie  between  z  and 
z  +  hz.  Suppose  however  that  only  two  values  are  possible  which 
we  may  denote  by  £  and  ^^ ;  then  we  must  suppose  that  f^  {z) 
vanishes  for  all  values  of  z  except  when  z  is  very  nearly  equal 
to  fi  or  to  ^i,  and  we  may  put 


ra 
J  b 


where  ^^  stands  for  the  part  of  the  integral  arising  from  values 
of  z  nearly  equal  to  ^^  and  qi  stands  for  the  part  of  the  integral 
arising  from  values  of  z  nearly  equal  to  f ^ ;  and  thus 

Pi+qi  =  l. 

fa  ^ 

Again,      zf^  (z)  dz  will  reduce  to  two  terms  arising  from  values 

of  z  nearly  equal  to  fj  and  ^^  respectively,  so  that  we  shall  have 

I  ^^(2;)  J^=£i?i  +  ft2'^• 


Similarly, 


Suppose  now  in  Art.  1002  that  7i  =  72  =  •••  =  7s  =  1 ;  then 
=  X  [iSlp,  +  ^^q^)  (p,  +  q^)  -  (£p,  +  ^,qy] 

=  ^ptqi  (S  -  ft)'. 


LAPLACE.  607 

And  there  is,  by  Art.  1002,  tlie  probability  —r-  I  e'^"^  dt  that 
Se  will  lie  between 

t  (5i?i  +  ?i^i)  -  2t/c  and  t  {t^,  +  ft^^)  +  2T/t. 
There  has  been  no  limitation  as  to  the  sign  of  f^  or  l^i- 

■  This  result  will  be  found  to  agree  with  that  given  by  Laplace 
on  his  page  423  ;  he  had  previously,  on  his  page  420,  treated  the 
particular  case  in  which  the  function /^  {£)  is  supposed  the  same  at 
every  trial,  so  that  the  suffix  i  becomes  unnecessary,  and  the  result 
simplifies  in  the  manner  which  we  have  explained  towards  the 
end  of  Art.  1002. 

1038.  An  important  consequence  follows  so  naturally  from  the 
investigation  in  the  preceding  Article,  that  in  order  to  explain  it  we 
will  interrupt  our  analysis  of  Laplace.  Suppose  that  fi  =  1  and 
fi  =  0,  for  all  values  of  i :  thus 

and  Sfi  becomes  equal  to  the  number  of  times  in  which  an  event 

happens  ovit  of  s  trials,  the  chance  of  the  happening  of  the  event 

2    /''■ 
being  pi  at  i}^  trial.     Thus  we  have  the  probability  -r-       e'^  dt 

that  the  number  of  times  will  lie  between 

%Pi  —  T^/'2Spiqi  and  S^i  +  r  V22^i^i. 

This  is  an  extension  of  James  Bernoulli's  theorem  to  the  case 
in  which  the  chance  of  the  event  is  not  constant  at  every  trial  ;  if 
we  suppose  that  pi  is  independent  of  i  we  have  a  result  practically 
coincident  with  that  in  Art.  993.  This  extension  is  given  by 
Poisson,  who  attaches  great  importance  to  it ;  see  his  Recherches 
sur  la  Prob.  ...,  page  246. 

1039.  If  instead  of  two  values  at  the  i*^  trial  as  in  Art.  1037, 
we  suppose  a  larger  number,  the  investigation  will  be  similar  to 


608  LAPLACE. 

that  already  given.     Denote  these  values  by  fj,  ft,  %»  ... ;  we  shall 
have 

-where  pi  +  qi  +  Wi+  ...  =  !'; 

Laplace  himself  takes  the  particular  case  in  which  the  function 
fi(z)  is  supposed  the  same  at  every  trial ;  see  his  pages  423 — 425. 

1040.  Laplace  proceeds  to  a  modification  of  the  problem  just 
considered,  which  may  be  of  more  practical  importance.  Nothing 
is  supposed  known  a  priori  respecting  the  chances,  but  data  are 
taken  from  observations.  Suppose  we  have  observed  that  in  /x^ 
trials  a  certain  result  has  been  obtained  v^^  times  :  if  /jl  more  trials 
are  made  determine  the  expectation  of  a  person  who  is  to  receive  f 
each  time  the  result  is  obtained,  and  to  forfeit,  f  each  time  the 
result  fails. 

The  analysis  now  is  like  that  which  we  have  given  at  the  end  of 

2    f'^ 
Art.  1036.     There  is  the  probability  -j-       e'^"^  dt  that  the  number 

of  times  the  result  is  obtained  will  lie  between 

But  if  the  result  is  obtained  a  times  in  fx  trials  the  advan- 
tage is 

o-f-  {fi  -  a)  f,  that  is,   c  (f  +  f)  -  yt^f. 

Hence  there  is  the  probability  above  assigned  that  the  advan- 
tage will  lie  between 

This  will  be  found  to  agree  substantially  with  Laplace's 
page  425. 

1041.  Laplace  passes  on  to  questions  connected  with  life  in- 
surances :  he  shews  that  the  stability  of  insurance  companies 
depends  on  their  obtaining  a  very  large  amount  of  business.  It 
has  been  pointed  out  by  Bienaym^,  that  if  the  consideration  of 


LAPLACE.  609 

compound  interest  is  neglected  we  shall  form  too  high  an  estimate 
of  the  stability  of  insurance  companies ;  see  Cournot's  Exposition 
de  la  Theorie  des  Chances... ^Rge  333:  se^  also  page  143  of  the 
same  work  for  a  formula  by  Bienayme  connected  with  the  result 
given  in  Ai't.  1038. 

1042.  Laplace's  tenth  Chapter  is  entitled  De  Tesperance  morale: 
it  occupies  pages  432 — 445.  This  Chapter  may  be  described  as 
mainly  a  reproduction  of  the  memoir  by  Daniel  Bernoulli,  which 
we  have  analysed  in  Arts.  377 — 393  ;  Laplace  himself  names  his 
predecessor.  Laplace  adds  the  demonstration  to  which  we  have 
referred  in  Art.  388  ;  see  his  pages  436,  437.  Laplace  also  applies 
the  theory  of  moral  expectation  to  an  example  connected  with  life 
annuities  ;  see  his  pages  442 — 444. 

The  following  example  in  inequalities  is  involved  in  Laplace's 
page  444.  If  a^,  a^,  a^,  ...  and  h^,  h^,  h^,  ...  are  series  both  in  in- 
creasing or  both  in  decreasing  order  of  magnitude 


is  greater  than 


a^\  +  a^\  +  o^\  +  . . .  +  OnK 

afi^  +  <^2^2  +  ^3^3  +  •  •  •  +  <^n^n 

a^  +  a^  +  a^+  ...  +  Gn   ' 


for  if  we  multiiDly  up  and  bring  all  the  terms  together,  we  find 
that  the  result  follows  from  the  fact  that  ara^  {cij.  —  a^  {hr  —  h^  is 
positive. 

Hence  too  if  one  of  the  two  series  is  in  increasing  and  one  in 
decreasing  order  of  magnitude  the  inequality  becomes  inverted. 

1043.  Laplace's  eleventh  Chapter  is  entitled  De  la  Prohahilite 
des  Umoig^iages:  it  occupies  pages  446 — 461. 

We  have  given  sufficient  indication  of  the  main  principle  of 
the  Chapter  in  Art.  735  ;  see  also  Art.  941. 

Laplace's  process  on  his  page  457,  although  it  leads  to  no  eiTor 
in  the  case  he  considers,  involves  an  unjustifiable  assumption ;  see 
Poisson,  Eecherches  siir  la  Pro6. ...page  112.  See  also  pages 
3  and  364  of  Poisson's  work  for  criticisms  bearing  on  Laplace's 
eleventh  Chapter. 

39 


610  LAPLACF. 

1044.  Laplace's  pages  464 — 484  are  headed  Additions;  see 
Arts.  916,  921.     There  are  three  subjects  discussed. 

I.  Laplace  demonstrates  Wallis's  theorem,  and  he  gives  an 
account  of  the  curious  way  in  which  the  theorem  was  discovered, 
although  it  cannot  be  said  to  have  been  demonstrated  by  its  dis- 
coverer. 

II.  Laplace  demonstrates  a  formula  for  A"s'  which  he  had 
formerly  obtained  by  a  bold  assumption  ;  see  Arts.  916,  966. 

III.  Laplace  demonstrates  the  formula  marked  (p)  on  page  168 
of  the  Theorie...des  Prob.;  see  Art.  917. 

1045.  The  first  Supplement  to  the  Theorie...des  Proh.  is  en- 
titled Sur  V application  du  Calcul  des  Prohabilites  d  la  Philosophie 
Naturelle ;  it  occupies  34  pages:  see  Art.  926.  The  title  of  the 
Supplement  does  not  seem  adapted  to  give  any  notion  of  the 
contents. 

1046.  We  have  seen  in  Art.  1009  that  in  Laplace's  theory  of 
the  errors  of  observations  a  certain  quantity  occurs  the  value  of 
which  is  not  known  a  priori,  but  which  may  be  approximately 
determined  from  the  observations  themselves.  Laplace  proposes 
to  illustrate  this  point,  and  to  shew  that  this  approximation  is  one 
which  we  need  not  hesitate  to  adopt  :  see  pages  7 — 11  of  the  first 
Supplement.  It  does  not  appear  to  me  however  that  much  con- 
viction could  be  gained  from  Laplace's  investigation. 

A  very  remarkable  theorem  is  enunciated  by  Laplace  on  page  8 
of  the  first  Supplement.  He  gives  no  demonstration,  but  says 
in  his  characteristic  way,  L'analyse  du  n°  21  du  seconde  Livre 
conduit  a  ce  theoreme  general....  The  theorem  is  as  follows: 
SupjDose,  as  in  Art.  1011,  that  certain  quantities  are  to  be  deter- 
mined by  the  aid  of  observations ;  for  simplicity  we  will  assume 
that  there  are  three  quantities  x,  y,  z.  Let  values  be  found  for 
these  quantities  by  the  most  advantageous  method,  and  denote 
these  values  by  o;^,  y^,  z^,  respectively.     Put 

aj  =  a?j  +  f ,     y  =  y^  +  V,     z  =  z^+^. 
Then  Laplace's  theorem  asserts  that  the  probability  of  the  simul- 


LAPLACE.  611 

taneoiis  existence  of  f,  77,  f,  as  values  of  the  errors  of  the  quantities 
to  be  determined,  is  23roportional  to  e~'^,  where 

I  am  compelled  to  omit  the  demonstration  of  this  theorem  for  want 
of  space ;  but  I  shall  endeavour  to  publish  it  on  some  other 
occasion. 

1047.  Laplace  next  supposes  that  six  elements  are  to  be 
determined  from  a  large  number  of  observations  by  the  most  ad- 
vantageous method.  He  arranges  the  algebraical  work  in  what 
he  considers  a  convenient  form,  supposing  that  we  wish  to  de- 
termine for  each  variable  the  mean  value  of  the  error  to  be  appre- 
hended, or  to  determine  the  probability  that  the  error  wdll  lie 
within  assigned  limits  ;  see  pages  11 — 19  of  the  first  Supplement. 
He  then,  on  his  pages  21 — 26,  makes  a  numerical  application,  and 
arrives  at  the  result  to  which  we  have  alreadv  referred  in  Art.  939. 

1048.  Laplace  observes  that  all  his  analysis  rests  on  the  as- 
sumption that  positive  and  negative  errors  are  equally  likely,  and 
he  now  proposes  to  shew  that  this  limitation  does  not  practically 
affect  the  value  of  his  results:  see  his  pages  19 — 21.  Here  again 
however  it  does  not  appear  to  me  that  much  conviction  would  be 
gained  from  Laplace's  investigation. 

1049.  The  first  Supplement  closes  with  a  section  on  the  Pro- 
bability of  judgments;  it  is  connected  with  the  eleventh  ChajDter  : 
see  Art.  1043. 

1050.  The  second  Supplement  is  entitled  Application  du 
Calcul  des  Prohahilites  aux  operations  geodesiques :  it  occupies  50 
pages:  see  Art.  927.     This  Supplement  is  dated  February  1818. 

This  Sup23lement  is  very  interesting,  and  considering  the  sub- 
ject and  the  author  it  cannot  be  called  difficult.  Laplace  shews 
how  the  knowledge  obtained  from  measuring  a  base  of  verification 
may  be  used  to  correct  the  values  of  the  elements  of  the  triangles 
of  a  survey.  He  speaks  favourably  of  the  use  of  repeating  circles; 
see  his  pages  5,  8,  20.  He  devotes  more  space  than  the  subject 
seems   to  deserve  to   discuss  an  arbitrary   method   proj^osed  by 

39—2 


(112  LAPLACE. 

Svanberg  for  deducing  a  result  from  observations  made  with  a  re- 
peating circle :  see  Laplace's  pages  82 — 35. 

Laplace  explains  a  method  of  treating  observations  which  he 
calls  the  method  of  situation,  and  which  he  considers  may  in 
some  cases  claim  to  be  preferable  to  the  "inost  advantageous  method 
explained  in  his  fourth  Chapter.  This  method  of  situation  had 
been  given  in  the  Mecanique  Celeste,  Livre  III.,  but  without  re- 
ceiving a  special  name:  see  Art.  1016.  Laplace  gives  an  investi- 
gation to  determine  when  the  inethod  of  situation  should  be  pre- 
ferred to  the  most  advantageous  method,  and  an  investigation  of  the 
value  of  a  combination  of  the  two  methods. 

1051.  The  third  Supplement  is  entitled  A^yplication  des 
formules  geodesiques  de  py^ohahilite,  d  la  meridienne  de  France; 
it  occupies  36  pages:  see  Art.  928. 

Laplace  begins  by  giving  a  numerical  example  of  some  of  the 
formulae  in  the  second  Supplement.  In  his  pages  7 — 15  he  gives 
what  he  calls  a  simple  example  of  the  application  of  the  geodesic 
formulae.  He  takes  a  system  of  isosceles  triangles,  having  their 
bases  all  parallel  to  a  given  line,  and  he  finds  the  errors  in  lengths 
arising  from  errors  in  the  angles.  The  investigation  is  like  that  in 
the  second  Supplement. 

Laplace  devotes  his  pages  16 — 28  to  discussions  respecting  the 
error  in  level  in  large  trigonometrical  surveys. 

Pages  29 — 36  contain  what  Laplace  calls  Methods  generale  du 
calcul  des prohabilites,  lorsquil  y  a  plusieurs  sources  d'erreurs. 

1052.  Here  we  close  our  account  of  the  Theorie  Analytique 
des  Prohahilites.  After  every  allowance  has  been  made  for  the  aid 
which  Laplace  obtained  from  his  predecessors  there  will  remain 
enough  of  his  own  to  justify  us  in  borrowing  the  words  applied  to 
his  Theory  of  the  Tides  by  a  most  distinguished  writer,  and  pro- 
nouncing this  also  "  to  be  one  of  the  most  splendid  works  of  the 
greatest  mathematician  of  the  past  age." 

For  remarks  which  will  interest  a  student  of  Laplace's  work  I 
may  refer  to  the  first  page  in  the  Appendix  to  De  Morgan's  Essay 
on  Probabilities ..  .'va  the  Cabinet  Cyclopaedia;  to  the  History  of  the 
Science  which  forms  the  introduction  to  Galloway's  Treatise  pub- 


LAPLACE.  C13 

lished  in  tlie  Encyclopcedia  Britannica;  to  the  work  of  Gouraud, 
pages  107 — 128 ;  and  to  various  passages  in  Dugald  Stewart's  Works 
edited  hy  Hamilton,  which  will  be  found  by  consulting  the  General 
Index  in  the  Supplementary  volume. 

Some  observations  by  Poisson  will  find  an  appropriate  place 
here:  they  occur  in  the  Comptes  Rendus... Yol.  IL  page  396. 

Sans  doute  LajDlace  s'est  montre  un  homme  de  genie  dans  la  meca- 
nique  celeste ;  c'est  lui  qui  a  fait  preuve  de  la  sagacite  la  plus  penetrante 
pour  decouvrir  les  causes  des  phenomenes ;  et  c'est  ainsi  qu'il  a  trouve  la 
cause  de  Tacceleration  du  mouvement  de  la  Lune  et  celle  des  grandes 
inegalites  de  Saturn e  et  de  Jupiter,  qu'Euler  et  Lagrange  avaient  cher- 
chees  infructueusement.  Mais  on  pent  dire  que  c'est  encore  plutot  dans 
le  calcul  des  probabilites  qu'il  a  ete  un  grand  geometre;  car  ce  sent  les 
nombreuses  ap[)lications  qu'il  a  faites  de  ce  calcul  qui  out  donne  naissauce 
au  calcul  aux  differences  fiuies  partielles,  a  sa  methode  pour  la  reduction 
de  certaines  integrales  en  series,  et  a  ce  qu'il  a  nomme  la  theorie  des  /onc- 
tions  generatrices.  Un  des  plus  beaux  ouvrages  de  Lagrange,  son  Me- 
moire  de  1775,  a  aussi  pour  occasion,  et  en  partie  pour  objet,  le  calcul 
des  probabilites.  Croyons  done  qu'un  sujet  qui  a  fixe  1' attention  de 
pareils  hommes  est  digne  de  la  notre;  et  tachons,  si  cela  nous  est  pos- 
sible, d'aj  outer  quelque  chose  a  ce  qu'ils  ont  trouve  dans  une  matiere 
aussi  difficile  et  aussi  interessante. 


APPENDIX. 


1053.  This  Appendix  gives  a  notice  of  some  writings  which 
came  under  my  attention  during  the  printing  of  the  book,  too 
late  to  be  referred  to  their  proper  2:)laces. 

105-i.  John  de  Witt's  tract  which  was  mentioned  in  the  fifth 
Chapter  has  been  recovered  in  modern  times,  and  printed  in  an 
Enghsh  translation.  See  Contributions  to  the  History  of  Insur- 
ance... by  Frederick  Hendriks,  Esq.  in  the  Assurance  Magazine, 
Yol.  II.  1852,  page  231.  For  some  remarks  on  John  de  Witt's  hypo- 
thesis as  to  the  rate  of  mortality,  see  page  393  of  the  same 
volume. 

Many  interesting  and  valuable  memoirs  connected  with  the 
history  of  Insurance  and  kindred  subjects  will  be  found  in  the 
volumes  of  the  Assurance  Magazine. 

1055.  A  memoir  on  our  subject  occurs  in  the  Actoruni  Eru- 
ditorum. .  .Supplemenia.  Tomus  ix.  Lipsise,  1729.  The  memoir  is 
entitled,  Johannis  Rizzetti Ludorunn  Scientia,  sive  Artis  conjectandi 
elementa  ad  alias  appUcata:  it  occupies  pages  215 — 229  and 
295—307  of  the  volume. 

It  appears  from  page  297  of  the  memoir  that  Daniel  Ber- 
noulli had  a  controversy  with  Rizzetti  and  Riccati  relating  to 
some  problems  in  chances ;  I  have  found  no  other  reference  to 
this  controversy.  Rizzetti  cites  the  Exercitationes  Mathematicce 
of  Daniel  Bernoulli ;  I  have  not  seen  this  book  myself,  which 
ajDpears  to  have  been  published  in  1721^. 

The  chief  point  in  dispute  may  be  said  to  be  the  proper  defi- 
nition of  expectation.  Suppose  that  A  and  B  play  together ;  let 
A  stake  the  sum  a,  and  B  stake  the  sum  h ;  suppose  that  there 
are  m  +  n  +  p  equally  likely  cases,  in  m  of  them  A  is  to  take  both 
the  stakes,  in  7i  of  them  B  is  to  take  both  the  stakes,  and  in  p  of 


APPENDIX.  615 

them  each  takes  his  own  stake.  Then  according  to  the  ordinary- 
principles  we  estimate  the  expectation  of  A  at 

m  {a  +  i)  +2^^ 
m  +  n +p     ' 

so  far  as  it  depends  upon  the  game  which  is  to  be  played.  Or  if 
we  wish  to  take  account  of  the  fact  that  ^  has  already  paid  down 
the  sum  a,  w^e  may  take  for  the  expectation 

mia  +h)  ■\-  pa           ,.    ,    .       mh  —  na 
— a,  that  is,  . 

Eizzetti  however  prefers  another  definition ;  he  says  that  A  has 

m  chances  out  of  7n  -{-n  +  p  of  gaining  the   sum  h ;  so  that  his 

7726 

expectation  is .     Rizzetti  tries  to  she^v  that  the  ordinary 

m  +  71  -\-p 

definition  employed  by  Montmort  and  Daniel  Bernoulli  leads  to 
confusion  and  error ;  but  these  consequences  do  not  really  follow 
from  the  ordinary  definition  but  from  the  mistakes  and  unskil- 
fulness  of  Rizzetti  himself 

The  memoir  does  not  give  evidence  of  any  power  in  the  sub- 
ject. Rizzetti  considers  that  he  demonstrates  James  Bernoulli's 
famous  theorem  by  some  general  reasoning  which  mainly  rests 
on  the  axiom,  Effectus  constans  et  immutabilis  pendet  a  causa 
constante,  et  immutabili.  On  his  page  224  he  gives  wdiat  he  con- 
siders a  short  investigation  of  a  problem  discussed  by  Huygens 
and  James  Bernoulli ;  see  Arts.  33,  103 :  but  the  investigation  is 
unsatisfactory,  and  shews  that  Rizzetti  did  not  clearly  understand 
the  j)roblem. 

1056.  I  am  indebted  for  a  reference  to  the  memoir  noticed 
in  the  preceding  Article  to  Professor  De  Morgan  who  derived  it 
from  Kahle,  Bihliothecce  Philosopliice  Struviance...GoiimgQn,  1740. 
2  Vols.  8vo.  Vol.  I.  p.  295.  Professor  De  Morgan  supplied  me 
from  the  same  place  with  references  to  the  following  works  which 
I  have  not  been  so  fortunate  as  to  obtain. 

Andrew  Budiger,  De  sensu  falsi  et  veri,  lib.  I.  cap.  xii.  et 
lib.  III. :  no  further  description  given. 

Kahle  himself  Elementa  logicce  probabilium,  methodo  mathe- 
matica...'RRlse  MagdeburgiccT,  1735,  8vo. 


616  APPENDIX. 

1057.  The  work  which  we  have  quoted  at  the  beginning  of 
Art.  347  contains  some  remarks  on  onr  subject;  they  form  part 
of  the  Introduction  a  la  Philosopliie,  and  occur  on  pages  82 — 93  of 
the  second  volume.  It  appears  from  page  XLVII  of  the  first  volume 
that  this  work  was  first  published  by  's  Gravesande  in  1736.  The 
remarks  amount  to  an  outline  of  the  mathematical  Theory  of  Pro- 
bability. It  is  interesting  to  observe  that  's  Gravesande  gives  in 
effect  an  example  of  the  inverse  use  of  James  Bernoulli's  theorem; 
see  his  page  85 :  the  example  is  of  the  kind  which  we  have  used 
for  illustration  in  Art.  125. 

1058.  The  result  attributed  to  Euler  in  Art.  131  is  I  find 
really  due  to  John  Bernoulli.  See  Johannis  Bernoulli... Opera 
Omnia,  Tomus  Quartus,  1742,  p.  22.     He  says, 

Atque  ita  satisfactum  est  ardenti  desiclerio  Fratris  mei,  qui  agnoscens 
summse  liujus  pervestigationem  difficiliorem  esse  qiiam  quis  putaverit, 
ingenue  fassus  est,  omnem  suam  industriani  fuisse  elusam  :  Si  quis  in- 
veniat,  inquit,  tiohisque  commu7iicet,  quod  i7idustriam  nostram  elusit 
hactenus,  magna s  de  nobis  gratias  ft  ret.  Yid.  Tractat.  de  Seriehus  inji- 
nitis,  jD.  254:.  Utinam  Frater  superstes  esset. 

1059.  An  essay  on  Probability  was  written  by  the  celebrated 
Moses  Mendelsohn ;  it  seems  to  have  been  published  in  his  Phi- 
losophische  Schriften  in  1761.  I  have  read  it  in  the  edition  of  the 
Philosophische  Schriften  which  appeared  at  Berlin  in  1771,  in  two 
small  volumes.  The  essay  occupies  pages  243 — 283  of  the  second 
volume. 

Mendelsohn  names  as  writers  on  the  subject,  Pascal,  Format, 
Huygens,  Halley,  Craig,  Petty,  Montmort,  and  De  Moivre.  Men- 
delsohn cites  a  passage  from  the  work  of  's  Gravesande,  which 
amounts  to  an  example  of  James  Bernoulli's  theorem  ;  and  Men- 
delsohn gives  what  he -considers  to  be  a  demonstration  of  the 
theorem,  but  it  is  merely  brief  general  reasoning. 

The  only  point  of  interest  in  the  memoir  is  the  following. 
Suppose  an  event  A  has  happened  simultaneously,  or  nearly  so, 
with  an  event  B;  we  are  then  led  to  enquire  whether  the  con- 
currence is  accidental  or  due  to  some  causal  connexion.     Men- 


APPENDIX.  617 

delsohn  says  that  if  the  concurrence  has  happened  n  times  the 

probability  that  there  is  a  causal  connexion  is ;  but  he  gives 

no  intimation  of  the  way  in  which  he  obtains  this  result.  He 
takes  the  following  illustration  :  suppose  a  person  to  drink  coffee, 
and  to  be  attacked  with  giddiness ;  the  concurrence  may  be  acci- 
dental or  there  may  be  some  causal  connexion  :  if  the  concurrence 

has  been  observed  n  times  the  probability  is that  the  o-id- 

diness  will  follow  the  drinking  of  coffee. 

If  we  apply  the  theorem  of  Bayes  and  Laplace,  and  suppose 

that  an  event  has  happened  n  times,  the  probability  that  it  will 

?i  +  1 
happen  at  the  next  trial  is  ^ ;  see  Art.  848.     It  is  certainly 

curious  that  Mendelsohn's  rule  should  agi-ee  so  nearly  with  this 
result  when  n  is  large,  but  it  is  apparently  only  an  accidental 
coincidence,  for  there  is  nothing  in  Mendelsohn's  essay  which 
suggests  that  he  had  much  knowledge  of  the  subject  or  any  great 
mathematical  power :  we  cannot  therefore  consider  that  he  in  any 
way  anticipated  Bayes. 

Mendelsohn  makes  his  rule  serve  as  the  foundation  of  some 
remarks  on  the  confidence  which  we  repose  on  the  testimony  of 
our  senses,  referring  especially  to  the  scepticism  of  Hume.  Men- 
delsohn also  touches  on  the  subjects  of  Free  Will  and  the  Divine 
Foreknowledge ;  but  as  it  appears  to  me  without  throwing  any 
light  on  these  difficult  problems. 

I  was  aware  that  Mendelsohn  had  written  on  Probability  from 
the  occurrence  of  his  name  in  Art.  840,  but  I  assumed  that  his 
essay  would  not  contain  any  matter  bearing  on  the  mathematical 
theory,  and  so  I  omitted  to  examine  it.  I  supply  the  omission 
at  the  request  of  the  late  Professor  Boole  ;  he  had  seen  a  reference 
to  Mendelsohn  in  some  manuscripts  left  by  Dr  Bernard,  formerly 
teacher  of  Hebrew  in  the  University  of  Cambridge,  and,  in  con- 
sequence of  this  reference,  expressed  a  wish  that  I  would  report 
on  the  character  of  the  essay. 

1060.  I  take  from  Booksellers'  Catalogues  the  titles  of  four 
works  which  T  have  never  seen. 


018  APPENDIX. 

Thubeuf.  EMmens  et  principes  de  la  royale  Arithm^tique 
aux  jettons,  etc.     12mo.  Paris,  1661. 

Marpurg,  F.  W.,  Die  Kunst,  sein  Gliick  spielend  zu  maclien. 
Hamburg,  1765.     4to. 

Fenn,  (I.)  Calculations  and  formulae  for  determining  the  Ad- 
vantages or  Disadvantages  of  Gamesters,...  1772.     4to. 

Frommichen  Ueber  Lelire  d.  Wahrsclieinl.  Braunscbw.  1 773 .  4 to. 

1061.  I  had  overlooked  a  passage  in  Montucla  which  bears 
on  the  point  noticed  in  Art.  990;  see  Montucla,  page  421.  It 
seems  that  a  mode  of  election  suggested  by  Condorcet  was  for 
some  time  adopted  at  Geneva.  The  defects  of  the  mode  were 
indicated  in  a  work  by  Lhuilier  entitled,  Examen  dii  mode  d'elec- 
tion  propose  en  fevrier  1793,  a  la  Convention  nationale  de  France^ 
et  adopts  d  Geneve  (1794,  en  8^). 

1062.  A  very  curious  application  of  the  Theory  of  Proba- 
bility was  stated  by  Waring;  see  his  Meditotiones  Algehraicce, 
3rd  Edition,  1782,  pages  xi,  69,  73.  For  example,  he  gives  a  rule  for 
ascertaining  the  number  of  imaginary  roots  in  an  equation,  and 
says  :  Haec  methodus  in  quadraticis  sequationibus  verum  prgebet 
numerum  impossibilium  radicum  :  in  cubicis  autem  ejus  proba- 
bilitas  inveniendi  impossibiles  radices  non  videtur  majorem  habere 
rationem  ad  probabilitatem  fallendi  quam  2:1. 

I  owe  this  reference  to  the  kindness  of  Professor  Sylvester  in 
sending  me  a  copy  of  his  remarkable  memoir  in  the  Philosophical 
Transactions  for  1864,  on  the  Real  and  Imaginary  roots  of  Alge- 
hi'aical  Equations.  Professor  Sylvester  had  independently  made 
the  same  kind  of  application ;  see  page  580  of  the  volume,  where 
he  says :  "  Like  myself,  too,  in  the  body  of  the  memoir  Waring 
has  given  theorems  of  probability  in  connexion  with  rules  of  this 
kind,  but  without  any  clue  to  his  method  of  arriving  at  them. 
Their  correctness  may  legitimately  be  doubted." 


CHRONOLOGICAL  LIST  OF  AUTHORS. 


The  figures  refer  to  the  pages  of  the  Volume. 


1606 

1617 

1654 

1654 

1657 
1657 

1662 
1666 
1670 
1671 
1679 
16S5 
1685 
1690 
1690 
1692 
1693 

i(>93 
1699 

1708 

1709 

1709 

1710 

1711 

1712 

1713 
1714 

1714 

1714 

1714 

1718 


PAGE 

Cardan i 

Buckley    26 

Kepler 4 

G  ALTLEO 4 

puteanus 27 

Pascal    7,  28 

Fehm  AT 7 

HUTGENS    22 

schooten  30 

Graunt 38 

Leibnitz    31 

Car  AMUEL 44 

John  DE  Witt    38,614 

Sauveur    46 

Wallis ..  34 

James  Bernoulli    47 

Petty 39 

James  Bernoulli    47 

Arbuthnot  49 

H  ALLEY 41 

Roberts    53 

Craig 54 

MoNTMORT 79 

Nicolas  Bernoulli    194 

Barbeyrac    196 

Arbuthnot  196 

De  Moivre  136 

's  Gravesande 197 

James  Bernoulli    58 

Montmort 79 

Nicolas  Bernoulli    199 

De  Moivre    199 

Browne     199 

De  Moivre   136 


728 
729 

730 
730 
730 

733 

734 
736 
738 
738 
739 
740 
742 

751 
751 

753 
754 
754 
756 

757 
757 
758 
760 
760 
761 
761 
762 

763 
764 
765 
765 
766 

767 
767 


PAGE 

Mairan     200 

Rizzetti    614 

Nicole   201 

Daniel  Bernoulli  213 

Cramer      221 

BuFFON 203 

Daniel  Bernoulli 222 

's  Gravesande     616 

De  Moivre    1 36 

Ham    203 

D.M 205 

Simpson 206 

John  Bernoulli 212 

EuLER    239 

K aestner 321 

DODSON 322 

Hoyle    322 

D'Alembert 258 

De  Moivre    1 36 

Simpson 211 

D'Alembert 259 

Clark    323 

Daniel  Bernoulli  224 

EULER    240 

D'Alembert 261 

Mendelsohn 616 

Mallet 325 

Bayes  and  Price 294 

EULF.R    243 

EULER      245 

Beguelin 328 

Daniel  Bernoulli 228,229 

Beguelin  331 

Michell    332 


620 


CHRONOLOGICAL  LIST   OF  AUTHORS. 


PAGE 

768    John  Bernoulli 335 

768  D'Alembert -272,  273,  285 

769  John  Bernoulli 325 

769    EuLER    •. 247 

769  Daniel  Bernoulli 231,  235 

770  Lagrange 301 

771  Lambert    335 

772  Mallet 337 

773  Laplace    473 

774  Laplace 464,465 

775  Lagrange 313 

776  Emerson   343 

777  Daniel  Bernoulli 236 

777      EULER     237 

777  BUFFON  344 

778  Laplace  476 

779  ^uss  349 

779  Laplace 484 

780  Fuss  350 

780  Prevost   432 

781  Prevost    432 

781     BoRDA    432 

781  condorcet  392 

782  condorcet  395 

782  Malfatti 434 

782  Laplace  485 

782  Waring    618 

783  Laplace    485,  486 

783     BiCQUILLEY    438 

783  CONDORCET   398 

784  CONDORCET  401 


PAGE 


784    D'Anieres    445 

784  Encyclopedie  Methodique    44  t 

785  Euler    256 

785  condorcet    351 

786  D'Anieres    445 

792    Lagrange     320 

792  Waring  446 

793  Trembley 411 

794  Ancillon 453 

794    Trembley 420 

794  Waring 452 

795  Trembley 413 

795  Laplace    487 

796  Trembley 423 

796  Prevost  and  Lhuilier 453 

797  Prevost  and  Lhuilier 461 

797    Trembley 426 

799    Trembley 426 

8or     Trembley 428 

802     Trembley 429 

809  Laplace  487 

810  Laplace  489 

812  Laplace  495 

813  Laplace  490 

814  Laplace  495 

815  Laplace  491 

816  Laplace  491 

818  Laplace  494 

820  Laplace  495 

822  Laplace  495 


INDEX. 


The  figures  refer  to  the  pages  of  the  Volume. 


Absent,  260,  441. 

Accius  Nsevius,  409. 

Airy,  589,  612. 

Ancillon,  453. 

Annuities,  4-2,  742,  320,  447. 

Arbuthnot,  49  to  53,  130,  193,  197,  '200. 

Arguments,  Probability  of,  70,  462. 

Arithmetical  Triangle,  17,  28  to  30,  64,  82. 

Assurance,  256,  441. 

Athenaeum,  38,  55,  501. 

Bacon,  503. 

Baily,  452. 
Barbeyrac,  196. 
Barrow,  2  1 . 
Bauhusius,  27. 

Bayes,  294  to  300,  378,  466,  476,  592. 
Bayle's  Dictionary,  12. 
Bernard,  617. 

Bernoulli,  James,  22,  24,  28,  39,  46,  47, 
56  to  77,  80,   93,  98,    122,    124,  147, 

279»  378,  46^,  553. 
Bernoulli,  Jolin,  40,  45,  57,  88,  91,  96,  98, 

113    to    116,     121,     135,    139,    210,    2T2, 

222,  616, 
Bernoulli,  Nicolas,  45,   58,  90,  91,    loi, 

105  to  134,  148,  157,  162,  193  to  199, 

210,  220,  243,  429,  536. 
Bernoulli,  Daniel,  42,  213  to  238,  265  to 

285,  293,   319,   377,  393,  423  to  428, 

434,  442,  469,  475,  489,  502,  601,609, 

614. 
Bernoulli,  John,  325  to  328,  442,  469. 
Bicquilley,  55,  438  to  441. 
Bienayme,  608. 
Binet,  292. 

Boole,  7,  505,  512,  544,  617. 
Borda,  391,  432  to  434,  548. 
Boscovich,  588. 
Bowditch,  478,  588. 
Breslau  Registers,  41,  226,  322. 
Browne,  23,  49,  199. 
Buckley,  26. 

BufFon,   203,  262,  275,  277,  285,  344  to 
349;  376,  386,  440. 


Bullialdus,  65. 
Buteo,   33. 

Calandrin,  149. 

Calculus  of  Operations,  505  to  511,  525, 

534- 
Canton,  294. 

Caramuel,  44  to  46. 

Carcavi,  8. 

Cardan,  i  to  4,  33. 

Carpenter,  Lord,  141. 

Castelli,  6. 

Cauchy,  20,  520,  526. 

Clark,  207,  323. 

Clavius,  33,  44. 

Combinations,  26  to  36,  64,  82,  150. 

Commercium  Epistolicum,  131. 

Condorcet,  41,  186,  261,  292,  351  to  410, 

432,  441,  456,  458,  539'  541.  548,  618, 
Cotes,  143,  588. 
Cournot,  222,  383,  544,  609. 
Craig,  54,  462,  500. 
Cramer,  221,  222,  345. 
Cranmer,  149. 
Cuming,  182. 

D'Alembert,  14,  23,  224,  227,  228,  253, 
256,  258  to  293,  331,  344,  377,  601. 

Dangeau,  Marquis  of,  47. 

D'Anieres,  445. 

Dante,  i,  323. 

De  Beaune,  127,  130. 

De  Ganiferes,  29. 

De  Haan,  513,  514. 

De  la  Hontan,  95. 

De  la  Roche,  459. 

De  M^re,  7,  8,  11,  63,  145,  502. 

De  Moivre,  43,  52,  54,  63,  78  to  94, 
100  to   105,   128,   T34  to  193,    199  to 

211,   250  to  253,   305,  315  to    325,   340, 

361,  378,  412,  421,  466,  468,  497,  527, 

535,  539^  541,  553- 
De  Morgan,  26,  49,  147,  346,  379,  400, 

452,  513.  514,  539»  552,  557:  591,  605, 
612,  615. 
Descartes,  21,  59,  132,  505. 


622 


INDEX. 


De  Witt,  37  to  41,  614. 
Diderot,  55,  260. 
Dodson,  322, 

Election,  modes  of,  374,  547,  618. 

Ellis,  544,  561,  578. 

Emerson,  343. 

EncydopecUe,   39,   55,   201,    258  to  265, 

286,  290,  441  to  445. 
Errors,   Theory  of,    236   to  238,   301  to 

309,  428,  442,  468  to  470,   484,  488, 

490,  561  to  589. 
Euler,  90,  237  to  257,   325  to  328,  422,, 

443,  489.  553,  588. 
Expectation,  213,  261,  392,  609,  614. 

Faulhaberus,  65. 

Fenn,  618. 

Eermat,  7  to  21,  35,  97j  M^- 

Eontaitie,  222,  261,  346. 

Eontana,  186. 

Foiitenelle,  46,  57,  78,  188. 

Forbes,  334. 

Ereret,  407. 

Frommichen,  618. 

Fuss,  69,  349. 

Gaeta,  186. 

Galileo,  4  to  6. 

Galloway,  48,  409,  552,  557,  589,  612. 

Games : 

Ace  of  Hearts,  49,  203. 

Backgammon,  49,  205. 

Bassette,  46,  69,  93,  116,  150,  260,  443. 

Bernoulli's,  Nicolas,  116. 

Bowls,  100,  140,  159,  207,  212,  324. 

Breland,  443. 

Cartes,  290. 

Cinq  et  Neuf,  69. 

Croix   ou  Pile,  258  to  265,  279,  281, 
292. 

Dice,  260. 

Esp^rance,  94. 

Eerme,  106. 

Gageure,  259,  263,  264. 

Hazard,  48,  53,  94,  163,  164,  205. 

Her,  106,  133,  429. 


Krabs,  444. 
Lansquenet,  91. 

Lotteries,  48,  53,   roo,   151,   203,206, 
245  to  256,  260,  325,  338,  421,  465, 

527- 
Noyau X,  95. 

Odd  and  Even,  200,  465,  473,  527- 
Oublieux,  100. 
Pari,  260. 

Passe-Dix,  45,  94,  444. 
Paume,  75,  125. 
Pharaon,  48,  80,  87,  116,  150,  152,  203, 

243»  345- 
Piquet,  94,  166. 
Quadrille,  152,  201. 
Qninquenove,  94. 
Rafle,  Raffling,  94,  164. 
Royal  Oak,  52. 
Tas,  106,  110,  124. 
Treize  or  Rencontre,  91,  105,  115,  120, 

15^5  239,  335,  452,  535- 

Trente  et  Quarante,  205,  444. 

Tiijaques,  69. 

Trois  Dez,  94. 

Whist,  52,  164,  445. 
Garve,  453. 
Gauss,  489,  588. 
Generating    Functions,    484,    497,    504, 

53O;  534. 
Gouraud,  i,  11,  16,  36,   37,   38,   39,  46, 

77.  293,  344,  409;  499.  613. 
Graunt,  37. 

's  Gravesande,  79,  130,  197,  616. 
Gregory,  514. 

Halley,  41  to  43,  8r,  161,  226,  268,  463. 

Ham,  49,  203  to  205. 

Hamilton,  127. 

Haygarth,  459. 

Hendriks,  614. 

Hermann,  57. 

Herschel,  335. 

Hoyle,  322,  445. 

Huygens,    14,   21  to    25,   40,   44  to  52, 

£^8  to  62,  81,   138  to   141,    143,    199, 

432,  444- 

Izquierdus,  44. 


INDEX. 


G23 


Jones,  82. 
Justell,  41. 

Kaestner,  321. 
Kahle,  615. 
Karstens,  42  7. 
Kepler,  4, 
Kersebooni^  241. 

Lacroix,  377. 

Lagrange,  178,  211,  249,  301  to  320,  428, 
466,  469,  478,  484,  505,  535.  613. 

Lambert,  71,  93,  335  to  337,  428,  459, 
462,  588. 

Laplace,  7,  123,  T57  to  163,  169  to  178, 
186,  201,  213  to  224,  228,  230,  234, 
250  to  253,  279,  287,  293,  299,  314, 
317,  347,  379'  400/409^0422,  428, 
459,  464  to  613. 

Laplace,  Comte  de,  532  to  534. 

Laplace's  Functions,  559. 

Least  Squares,  560,  575. 

Leibnitz,  12,  r4,  21,  22,  31  to  33,39,  47> 

56,  73»  79.  502,  505. 
Leslie,  26. 

Lhuilier,  618.     See  Prevost  and  Lhuilier. 
Libri,  I,  2,  5,  6. 
Loc     ,50. 
Longomontanus,  45. 
Lubbock  aud  Drinkwater,  11,  23,  33,  37, 

4h  48,  50;  54;  55,  299. 
Lully,  44. 

M.,  205. 

Maclaurin,  192. 

Mairan,  200. 

Malebranche,  78,  126. 

Malfatti,  235,  434  to  438. 

MaUet,  325,  337  to  343,  350. 

Mar  pur  g,  618. 

Maseres,  34,  59,  65. 

Mayer,  588. 

Mead,  199. 

Mecanique  Celeste,  478,  487,  514,  588. 

Mechanique  du  Feu,  131. 

T^Iend  1    hn,  453,  uiO. 

Mercator,  65. 

Merian,  -.6. 

Michaelis,  93. 


IVIicheU,  332  to  335,  393,  491. 

Miclielsen,  427. 

Mill,  262,  356,  409,  500. 

Monsoury,  L'Abb^  de,  107. 

Montmort,  2,  36,  44  to  47,  55,  58,  78  to 

142,    159,    167,   174,    187,   195  to  203, 

209,  212,  338  to  343,  429,  444. 
Montucla,  II,  12,  16,  22,  26,  38,   39,   42, 

46,  48,    79,    133,    222,    224,   261,   292, 

^93>  316,  332,  618. 
Mortality,  37  to  43,  240,  268,  285. 
Motte,  23,  48. 

Napoleon,  495  to  497. 

Necker,  259,  264. 

Neiimann,  41. 

Newton,  21,  54,  86,  126,  131,   132,    135, 

141.  187,  324,  485. 
Nicole,  201  to  203. 
Nozzolini,  5. 
Numbers  of  Bernoulli,  65,  152,  191. 

Orbais,  L'Abb^  d',  107. 
Oettinger,  175. 

Pacioli,  I. 

Pascal,  7  to  21,  28  to  30,40,66,  96,  128, 

277,  500,  502. 
Payne,  324. 
Peacock,  26, 

Permutations,  34,  64,  67,  150. 
Peterson,  54. 
Petty,  39,   81. 
Peverone,  i. 
Poisson,  7,  206,  222,  410,  489,  544,  556 

to  561,  567,  571,  576,  607,  609,  613. 
Pre  motion  Ph  tjsiq  ue,  131. 
Prestet,  28,  36,  64,  65. 
Prevost  and   Lhuilier,    54,  60,   71,   384, 

414,  432,  453  to  461. 
Price,  294  to  300,  378,  476. 
Problems: 

Arbuthnot's,  53,  209. 

Bernoulli's,  James,  67,  338,  350. 

Bernoulli's,  Daniel,  231  to  235,   319, 
434  to  436,  558,  560. 

Births  of  boys  and  girls,  130,  193,  196 
to  198,  235,  415  to  420,  480  to  484, 

593.  597. 


G24< 


INDEX. 


Problems  : 

Buffon's,  260,  347,  59°' 

Cuming's,  18-2. 

Duration  of  Marriages,  229,  335,  426, 

602. 
Duration  of  Play,  61,  loi  to  105,  147, 
167  to  183,   209,   317  to  320,  448, 

465.  474,  476,  489,  535- 
Inclination  of  Planes  of  Orbits,  222  to 

224,  273,  475,  487,  542. 
Laplace's  on  Comets,  491  to  494. 
Petersburg,  134,  220  to  222,  259  to  262, 

275,  280,  286  to  289,  332,  345,  393> 

470. 
Points,    8    to    19,  59,  96  to  99,    137^ 

146,  201  to  203,  316,  412,  468,  474, 

528,  532. 
Poisson's,  561  to  568. 
Eun  of  Events,  184  to  186,  208,  324, 

361  to  368,  473- 
Small-pox,  224  to  228,  265  to  286,  423, 

601. 
Waldegrave's,  122  to   125,    139,    162, 

199,  3^5j  535- 
Woodcock's,  147  to  149. 

Puteanus,  27. 

Kacine,  500. 

Riccati,  614. 

Kizzetti,  614. 

Eoberts,  53,  136,  137,  159,  1^4. 

Roberval,  8,  12  to  15. 

Rudiger,  615. 

Saurin,  58. 

Sauveur,  46,  201. 

Schooten,  22,  26,  30,  64,  67. 

Schwenter,  33. 

Series,   65,    73  to   75,  85,   89,  121,  125, 

178  to  181,  210,  313,  426,  464. 
Simpson,  53,  206  to  212,  236,  305,  309. 
Smart,  187. 
Stevens,  149,  164. 
Stewart,  Dugald,  4,  349>  409»  45 3>  458, 

502,  503,613. 
Stifel,  33. 


Struve,  334. 
Sussmilch,  320. 
Svanberg,  612, 
Sylvester,  618. 

Tacquet,  36. 
Tartaglia,  i. 
Taylor,  162. 
Terrot,  457. 
Tetens,  427. 
Theorems : 

Eayes's,  73,  294  to  300,  398,  410,  557, 

603. 
Bernoulli's,  James,  71  to  73,  i3i>  183, 
198,  360,   393,  548,  554,  556,   607. 
Binomial,  65,  82. 
De  Moivre's  on   Dice,    84,    138,    146, 

189,  208,  305,  350,  4^8,  542. 
De  Moivre's  approximation,  138,   144, 

207. 
Euler's,  192. 
Stirling's  72,   t88,  235,  467,  485,  520, 

549.  553- 
Van  derm  onde's,  451. 

Wallis's,  610. 
Thomson,  49. 
Thubeuf,  618. 
Tltius,  54. 

Trembley,  no,  160,  230,  250,  411  to  431. 
Trial  by  Jury,  388. 
Turgot,  352. 

Van  Hudden,  38. 
Varignon,  114. 
Vastel,  59. 
Voltaire,  407,  409. 

Vossius,  28. 

Waldegrave,  122,  134. 

Wallis,   21  to  28,  34  to  36,  59,  65,    143, 

160,  498,  505. 
Waring,  446  to  452,  463,  618. 
Watt,  49,  322. 
Woodcock,  147,  148. 

Young,  463. 


THE    END. 


CAMBRIDGE  :    PRINTED    AT   THE   UNIVERSITY   PKESS.