Skip to main content

Full text of "On a reformulation of Cournot-Nash equilibria"

See other formats


UNIVERSITY  OF 

ILLINOIS  LIBRARY 

AT  URBANA-CHAMPAIGN 

330K3TA.CK3 


Digitized  by  the  Internet  Archive 

in  2011  with  funding  from 

University  of  Illinois  Urbana-Champaign 


http://www.archive.org/details/onreformulationo1328khan 


BEBR 

FACULTY  WORKING 
PAPER  NO.  1328 


On  A  Reformulation  of  Cournot-Nash  Equilibria 

M.  Ali  Khan 
Ye  Neng  Sun 


College  of  Commerce  and  Business  Administration 
Bureau  of  Economic  and  Business  Research 
University  of  Illinois,  Urbana-Champaign 


BEBR 


FACULTY  WORKING  PAPER  NO.  1328 
College  of  Commerce  and  Business  Administration 
University  of  Illinois  at  Urbana-Champaign 
February  1987 


On  a  Reformulation  of  Cournot-Nash  Equilibria 

M.  Ali  Khan,  Professor 
Department  of  Economics 

Ye  Neng  Sun 
Department  of  Mathematics 


On  a  Reformulation  of  Cournot-Nash  Equilibria* 


by 


M.  Ali  Khan*  and  Ye  Neng  Sun** 


January  1987 


Abstract.   We  present  variations  on  a  theme  of  Mas-Coleil  and  report 
results  on  the  existence  of  Cournot-Nash  equilibrium  distributions  in 
which  individual  action  sets  depend  on  the  distribution  of  actions  and 
the  payoffs  are  represented  by  relations  that  are  not  necessarily 
complete,  or  transitive. 

*This  research  was  supported  in  part  by  the  Bureau  of  Business  and 
Economic  Research  at  the  University  of  Illinois  and  in  part  by  an  NSF 
grant.   Both  sources  of  support  are  gratefully  acknowledged.   The 
second  author  would  also  like  to  acknowledge  with  gratitude  the 
constant  help  and  encouragement  of  Professor  Peter  Loeb. 

Department  of  Economics,  University  of  Illinois,  1206  South  Sixth 
Street,  Champaign,  IL   61820. 

Department  of  Mathematics,  University  of  Illinois,  1409  West  Green 
Street,  Urbana,  IL   61801. 


1.   Introduction 

In  [29],  Mas-Colell  showed  the  existence  of  a  Cournot-Nash 
equilibrium  distribution  for  games  with  a  compact  metric  space  of 
actions  and  with  continuous  payoffs.   Mas-Colell ?s  result  was 
generalized  in  [22]  to  situations  where  the  space  of  actions  is  not 
necessarily  metric,  and  hence  not  necessarily  separable,  and  where  the 
payoffs  need  only  be  upper  semicontinuous  in  the  individual  actions. 

The  economics  of  this  problem  go  back  to  Cournot  [7].   A  player  is 
characterized  by  his  action  set  A  and  his  payoff  function  u( * )  which 
depends  not  only  on  the  action  taken  but  also  on  the  probability 
distribution  of  the  actions  taken  by  everybody  else.   In  equilibrium, 
each  player,  in  choosing  his  best  action,  leads  to  the  same  distribution 
on  the  (common)  action  space  on  which  his  choice  is  conditioned.   Thus, 
the  problem  of  finding  a  Cournot-Nash  equilibrium  distribution  is  a 
natural  fixed  point  problem  though  the  original  formulation  of  Cournot 
predated  the  discovery  of  fixed  point  theorems. 

Stripped  of  their  economic  motivation,  the  results  constitute  an 

interesting  application  of  the  Ky  Fan,  Glicksberg  fixed  point  theorem 

[11,13]   to  a  problem  that  is  without  an  explicit  linear  structure  and, 

as  such,  essentially  topological.   The  data  of  the  problem  consists  of 

a  compact  Hausdorff  space  A;  the  space  /^(A)  of  Radon  probability 

measures  endowed  with  the  topology  of  weak  *  convergence  (as  in  [34]  or 

[37]);  the  space  LC,  of  continuous  real  valued  functions  on  A  x  fVl(A) 

A 

endowed  with  the  sup-norm  topology  (as  in  [29]);  and  a  Radon  probability 
measure  y  on  vL.«   The  problem  is  to  find  a  Radon  probability  measure 

t  on  A  x  U~k   such  that  the  raarginal  of  t  on  C(.k>    T    ,  equals  u  and 

A'  u. 


-2- 

such  that  t  gives  full  measure  to  the  set  {(a,u)  e  (A  x  UcA):  u(a,x.)  > 
u(x,t  )  for  all  x  e  A},  a  set  which,  it  bears  emphasis,  is  conditioned 

A 

on  T.  and  hence  on  t. 
A 

In  this  paper,  we  present  a  reformulation  of  this  basic  problem  by 
(i)    dispensing  with  payoff  functions  and  focussing  instead  on 

preference  relations; 
(ii)   allowing  strategy  or  action  sets  to  depend  on  the  distribution 

of  actions. 
In  terms  of  (i),  we  consider  two  classes  of  preference  relations,  one 
in  which  preferences  are  reflexive,  transitive  and  continuous,  though 
not  necessarily  complete,  and  the  other  in  which  transitivity  is 
replaced  by  a  suitable  convexity  assumption.   In  equilibrium  theory, 
Schmeidler  [32]  was  the  first  to  work  with  incomplete  but  transitive 
preferences  while  incomplete  and  non-transitive  preferences  date  to 
Mas-Colell  [28];  also  see  [13]  and  [35].   It  should  be  noted  that  our 
second  setting  departs  from  [29]  and  [22]  and  explicitly  brings  in  a 
linear  topological  structure  on  the  action  space  A.   The  motivation  for 
extension  (ii)  goes  back  at  least  to  Debreu's  1952  paper  [8]. 

Important  as  these  extensions  are  from  an  economic  point  of  view, 
they  also  add  to  the  technical  diversity  of  our  problem.   Under  our 
reformulation,  the  question  we  pose  involves  the  interplay  between  the 
compact  Hausdorff  space  A,  the  space  /VL(A) ,  the  hyperspace  J~t(A   x  A) 
of  closed  subsets  of  A  x  A  endowed  with  a  "suitable"  topology,  the 
space  of  continuous  functions  ^O  (A)  from  Vfl_(A)  to  a  subspace  of  ~J~1 
(A  x  A)  endowed   with  a  suitable  topology,  and  finally  a  Radon  measure 


-3- 

on   (A).   Our  search  for  a  suitable  topology  on  a  particular  subspace 
of  the  hyperspace  Irr  (A  x  A)  leads  us  to  "neighboring"  economic  agents 
as  formalized  by  Kannai  [19],  Debreu  [9],  Hildenbrand  [16,17],  Grodal 
[15],  Chichilnisky  [5]  and  Back  [2].   Moreover,  the  setup  of  our 
problem  leads  us  to  formalize  "neighboring"  economic  agents  in  the 
presence  of  externalities. 

The  plan  of  the  paper  is  as  follows.   Section  2  is  devoted  to  the 
formalization  of  neighboring  economic  agents  in  the  presence  of 
externalities.   In  this  section,  we  motivate  our  formalization  by 
relating  it  to  previous  work.   Section  3  is  devoted  to  mathematical 
preliminaries.   This  section  enables  us  to  develop  the  necessary 
terminology  and  notation  and  presents  the  mathematical  results  on  which 
our  formulations  depend.   Section  4  presents  the  model  and  results  and 
Section  5  collects  separately  two  results  on  the  existence  of  maximal 
elements  in  compact  sets.   These  are  essential  ingredients  in  the  proofs 
which  follow  in  Section  6.   References  and  proofs  for  the  technical 
results  in  Section  3  are  presented  in  Section  7. 

2.   Neighboring  Economic  Agents  in  the  Presence  of  Externalities 
In  a  pioneering  paper  circulated  in  1964,  Kannai  [19]  gave  a 
formalization  of  the  intuitive  idea  that  one  economic  agent  is 
"similar"  or  "close"  to  another.   Since  an  economic  agent  is 
characterized  by  his  preferences  and  endowments,  this  formalization 
amounted,  in  particular,  to  endowing  the  space  of  preference  relations 
with  a  topology.   Kannai  considered  a  setting  in  which  each  agent's 
preference  relation  >  is  defined  on  the  non-negative  orthant  of  n- 
diraensional  Euclidean  space  and  that  there  is  enough  structure  on  > 


-4- 


that  it  can  be  represented  by  a  utility  function  u(>,*)  on  R  .   He 
could  then  define  "closeness"  of  two  preference  relations  >  ,  >'  by  the 
metric  d  where 


|u(>,x)-u(>'  ,  x)| 

d(>,>')  =  Max    = . 

x  E  R^     1  +  |x|2 

An  alternative  way  of  viewing  Kannai's  work  is  to  say  that  he  endows 
the  space  of  monotonic  preference  relations  CK.  with  the  weakest 
Hausdorff  topology  making  the  set  {(x,y,>)  e  r"  x  r"  x  0\   :   x  >  y} 
closed. 

In  a  subsequent  contribution,  Debreu  [9]  exploited  the  observation 
that  continuous  preference  relations  can  be  injectively  mapped  into  the 
space  of  closed  subsets  of  the  product  space  and  hence,  in  the  context 
of  a  metric  space  of  commodities,  can  be  endowed  with  the  topology 
induced  by  the  Hausdorff  metric.   Debreu  also  observed  that  a 
uniformity,  rather  than  a  metric,  would  suffice  for  his  results. 

This  identification  of  a  preference  relation  with  a  closed  subset 
of  the  product  of  the  underlying  commodity  space  prompts  one  to  consider 
any  topology  on  the  space  of  closed  subsets  of  a  topological  space,  the 
hyperspace  of  that  topological  space,  as  potentially  relevant  to  the 
problem  of  defining  "neighboring"  economic  agents.   The  relative  merit 
of  one  topology  as  opposed  to  another  would  then  depend  on  the  economic 
problem  that  was  being  studied.   Accordingly,  in  [16],  Hildenbrand 
worked  with  the  topology  of  closed  convergence.   He  was  motivated,  in 
part,  by  the  fact  that  the  Hausdorff  metric  topology  proposed  by  Debreu 
is  not  separable  whereas  the  topology  of  closed  convergence  is  not  only 
separable  but  also  metrizable.   Moreover,  on  the  space  of  monotonic 


-5- 

preferences,  this  topology  coincides  with  that  proposed  by  Kannai. 
Hildenbrand  allowed  consumption  sets  to  differ  among  agents  but  stayed 
within  the  context  of  n-dimensional  Euclidean  space.   On  all  of  this, 
see  [17,  Section  1.2]  for  details.   Hildenbrand' s  work  was  extended  by 
Grodal  [15],  and  more  recently  by  Back  [2],  but  both  remain  in  R  . 

Chichilnisky  [5],  on  the  other  hand,  was  motivated  in  part  by  a 
search  for  a  topology  that  was  sensitive  to  the  Borel  measure  of  the 
"lower  contour  set"  of  a  preference  relation.   Accordingly,  she 
formalized  the  idea  of  "neighboring"  economic  agents  through  the  use  of 
the  order  topology  on  the  space  of  closed  subsets  of  the  product  of  a 
connected,  normal  space.   She  showed,  in  particular,  that  her  formal- 
ization led  to  a  topology  on  the  space  of  agents  that  was  strictly 
finer  than  that  provided  both  by  the  Hausdorff  metric  as  well  as  the 
closed  convergence  topologies  in  the  setting  of  a  compact  metric  space 
of  commodities. 

None  of  this  literature  allows  for  "externalities"  in  consumption. 
Put  another  way,  it  does  not  allow  consumption  sets  and  preference 
relations  to  respond  to  changes  in  the  "actions"  of  other  economic 
agents.   Such  dependence  is,  of  course,  an  essential  aspect  of  the 
Cournot-Nash  problem  as  can  be  seen  in  the  original  formulations  of 
Nash  [30]  and  Debreu  [8].   Nash  and  Debreu,  however,  considered  games 
with  a  finite  set  of  players  and,  in  such  a  setting,  allowed  each 
player's  strategy  set  and  payoff  function  to  depend  continuously  on 
the  action  of  each  and  every  other  player.   In  the  context  of  games 
with  a  continuum  of  players,  the  situation  is  much  less  straightforward, 
We  turn  to  this. 


-6- 

One  can  discern  four  distinct  formulations  of  "externalities"  in 
games  with  a  continuum  of  players.   Two  of  these  go  back  to  Schmeidler 
[33]  in  the  context  of  a  measure  of  space  of  players.   Under  the  first 
formulation,  Schmeidler  allows  each  player's  payoff  function  to  depend 
on  the  actions  taken  by  almost  all  players  as  embodied  in  the  equivalence 
class  of  measurable  functions  from  the  space  of  players  to  a  common 
strategy  set  in  R  .   Schmeidler' s  formulation  has  been  the  object 
of  extensive  work;  see,  for  example,  [20],  [21],  [25],  [38]  and  their 
references.   Under  the  second  formulation,  Schmeidler  specializes  to  a 
situation  under  which  each  player's  payoff  is  made  to  depend  on  the 
"average  response"  of  the  other  players.   This  average  response  is 
formalized  as  an  integral  of  the  "actions"  or  "plays"  of  the  other 
players.   This  formulation  has  also  been  extended  to  situations  when 
the  payoffs  are  represented  by  preference  relations  over  strategy  sets 
that  are  subsets  of  a  Banach  space,  see  [20]  and  the  references  therein. 

The  third  formulation  is  due  to  Mas-Colell  [29].   Unlike  Schmeidler's 
first  formulation,  Mas-Colell  also  limits  himself  to  dependence  on  the 
"average  response"  but  formalizes  this  response  as  a  distribution , 
rather  than  an  integral,  of  the  actions  of  the  other  players.   Thus,  if 
A  denotes  the  common  strategy  set  and  /^-(A) ,  the  space  of  probability 
measures  on  A,  the  payoff  functions  in  Mas-Colell  are  continuous  real- 
valued  functions  on  A  x  /vL(A). 

In  [22.]  ,  the  payoff  functions  of  Mas-Colell  are  viewed  in  a 
different  way  and  this  gives  us  our  fourth  formulation.   Under  this 
formulation,  a  continuous  real-valued  function  on  A  x/H_(A)  is  viewed 
as  a  family  of  continuous  real-valued  functions  on  A  and  parameterized 


-7- 

by  elements  of  /yL(A),  i.e.,  as  a  function  from  /HlA)  into  R  .   We 
shall  use  this  alternative  viewpoint  to  present  the  formulation  of 
externalities  and  dependence  that  is  studied  in  this  paper.   This 
can  now  be  used  to  generalize  the  work  of  Kannai ,  Debreu,  Hildenbrand 
and  Chichilnisky  to  situations  with  externalities. 

An  economic  agent  or  a  player  is  now  characterizated  as  a  continuous 
function  from  /fl(A)  to  the  space  of  preference  relations  on  A,  ^(A). 
Thus,  for  any  f  e  s£(k)    and  any  t  e  /tA_(A) ,     f  (t)  gives  a  strategy 
set  and  a  preference  relation  defined  on  that  strategy  set.   Two 
economic  agents  or  players,  f  and  g,  are  considered  to  be  "close"  if  f 
and  g  are  "close."   Our  formulation  thus  proceeds  in  two  distinct 
steps.   In  the  first  place,  using  the  topology  on  A,  we  endow  the  space  <J 
(A)  with  a  topology.   This  could  be  any  of  the  topologies  discussed  in 
the  first  part  of  this  section.   Next,  and  dependent  on  the  topology  on 

j7"(A),  we  endow  the  space  of  continuous  functions  from  /H.(A)  to  \j 
(A)  with  a  suitable  topology.   This  typically  involves  the  compact-open 
topology  and  another  topology  that  we  introduce  and  that  seems  more 
natural  for  our  problem.   However,  a  discussion  of  these  necessarily 
involves  a  more  formal  exposition. 

3.   Mathematical  Preliminaries 

Let  A  be  a  compact  Hausdorff  space  and  J-f(k)    denote  the  space  of 
closed  subsets  of  A.   Note  that  the  empty  set  <J>  is  an  element  of  ^//(A). 

We  shall  say  that  P  e  Jj   (A  x  A)  is  reflexive  if  (a, a)  e  P  for  all  a  e 

c  c 

A  and  that  P  is  complementedly  transitive  if  (a,b)  e  P  ,  (b,c)  e  P 

c        c 
implies  (a,c)  e  P  where  P  represents  the  complement  of  P  in  A  x  A  and 


-8- 


a,b,c  are  arbitrary  elements  in  A.   Any  (x,y)  e  P   can  be  read  as  "x  is 

preferred  to  y"  and  alternatively  denoted  x  >  y.   Analogously,  any 

(x,y)  e  P  can  be  read  as  "y  is  preferred  or  indifferent  to  x"  and 

alternatively  denoted  y  >  x.   For  any  B  e  Crf(A)tB  t    <f>,  let 

Jr n(A)  =  {P  e  >-/(B  x  B)  :  P  is  reflexive  and  complementedly 

transitive} , 

(A)  -     LJ  9R(A). 
Be  #(A) 

M  B  *    <j> 

^(A)  represents  the  space  of  preference  relations  and  we  shall  view 

it  as  a  subspace  of  J-f  (A  x  A)  endowed  with  one  of  two  possible 

topologies. 

The  first  topology  we  consider  is  the  topology  of  closed 

convergence  which  was  first  applied  in  equilibrium  theory  by 

Hildenbrand  [16]  and  proposed  by  Mertens  (see  [17,  page  108]).   This 

topology  has  as  its  sub-base  sets  of  the  following  form 

{F   e   ^(A   x  A)    :    FO  K  =   <j> }   and    {F    e  J"/  (A  x   A)    :    F  r\  G   *<J>} 

where  K  and  G  are  respectively  compact  and  open  subsets  of  A  x  A.  For 
more  details  into  this  topology,  the  reader  is  referred  to  [17,26]  and 
their  references.   We  shall  need  the  following  preliminary  result. 

Theorem  3.1.   If  A  is  a  compact  Hausdorff  space,  then  Jr  ( A )  is  a  compact 
Hausdorff  space  in  the  topology  of  closed  convergence. 

The  second  topology  that  we  consider  is  the  order  topology  first 
applied  in  equilibrium  theory  by  Chichilnisky  [5].   Consider  the  subset 
J-i    (A  x  A)  of  5/(A  x  A)  given  by 

J/  (A  x  A)  =  (  B  e  J/(A  x  A)  :  B  =  cl  Int(B)} 


-9- 


where  cl  and  Int  denote  closure  and  interior  respectively.   The  space 

h~U    (A  x  A)  can  be  endowed  with  an  order  structure  >  under  which  for 

any  X,Y  in   7/  (A  x  A) 
o 

X  ">  Y   if  and  only  if  Y  C  Int(X). 

Following  [5,  especially  footnote  10],  r%\   (A  x  A)  can  be  endowed  with 
a  topology,  the  order  topology,  which  has  its  sub-base  sets  of  the 
following  form: 

{X  e  3J   (A  x  A)  :  X>  Y)  and  (X  e  7"/  (A  x  A)  :  Y  >  X} 

for  any  Y  in  3-\   (A  x  A).   Let   5  (A)  =  M  (A  x  A)  (~\     ?(A). 

J  o  o         o 

We  can  state 

Theorem  3.2.   If  A  is  a  compact  Hausdorff  space,  then  j-j   (A  x  A) 
endowed  with  the  order  topology  is  a  completely  regular  space  and  hence 
the  relative  topology  on  jr   (A)  is  completely  regular. 

In  [5],  it  is  shown  that  the  order  topology  is  finer  than  the 
topology  of  closed  convergence  in  the  case  when  A  is  compact  metric. 
Our  next  result  offers  a  generalization  of  this  to  a  non-metric  setting. 

Theorem  3.3.   If  A  is  a  compact  Hausdorff  space,  then  the  order 

topology  on  j\  (A  x  A)  is  finer  than  the  topology  of  closed  convergence 

on  ~U    (A  x  A). 
—    o 

Next,  we  consider  the  space  of  Radon  probability  measures  defined 
on  Qj(A),  the  Borel  a-algebra  on  A.   Denote  this  space  by  n\.(A)    and 
endow  it  with  the  relative  weak  *  (or  narrow)  topology  (see  [34]  or 
[37]  for  details).   We  can  now  state  the  following  preliminary  result. 


-10- 

Theorem  3.4.   If  A  Is  a  compact  Hausdorff  space,  /W(A)  is  a  compact 
Hausdorff  space  in  the  (relative)  narrow  topology. 

Our  final  set  of  preliminary  concepts  concerns  the  space  of 
continuous  functions  from  /Vt(A)  into  the  space  of  preference  relations. 
When  the  space  of  preference  relations  jf (A)  is  endowed  with  the 
topology  of  closed  convergence,  we  shall  denote  the  space  of  continuous 
functions  from  nA~(A)    into   \7(A)  by  ,<>(A) .   When  the  space  of 
preference  relations  is  chosen  from  J-f   (A  x  A)  and  endowed  with  the 
order  topology,  we  shall  use  the  notation  J^.    (A)  for  the  space  of 
continuous  functions  from   ^-(A)  into  ^r   (A).   We  shall  endow  the 
spaces  s\_^(A)    and  aZ>   (A)  with  one  of  two  possible  topologies. 

The  first  topology  that  we  consider  on  ^O(A)  is  the  graph  topology. 
This  is  the  relativization  of  the  topology  of  closed  convergence  on 
nA^(A)    x  nJCA)  to  the  space  consisting  of  the  graphs  of  the  elements  in 
A^,(k).      Accordingly,  we  shall  say  that  a  net  {f  }  chosen  from  •-C-(A) 

converges  to  an  element  f  in  ^o-(A)  if  and  only  if  the  graph  of  f  , 

v 
Grf  ,  converges  in  the  topology  of  closed  convergence  to  Grf . ,  Since 

f   and  f  are  continuous  functions  and  their  range  is  a  Hausdorff  space, 

their  graphs  are  closed  subsets  of  /HlA)  x  >j(A).   Moreover,  given 

Theorems  3.1  and  3.4,  /^L(A)  x  vj  (A)  is  compact  and  hence  the  topology 

is  well  defined  (see  [23]).   Indeed,  one  can  say  more. 

Theorem  3.5.   If  A  is  a  compact  Hausdorff  space,  then  ,0-(A)  endowed 
with  the  graph  topology  is  Hausdorff  and  completely  regular. 

The  second  topology  that  we  consider  on  /\^(A)  is  the  compact-open 
topology.   This  has  as  its  sub-base  sets  of  the  following  form: 


-11- 

ff  e  ^(A)  :  f(K)   C   U)  =  (K,U),  K  compact,  U  open. 

The  relationship  between  the  topology  of  closed  convergence  and  the 
compact-open  topology  is  given  by  the  following  result. 

Theorem  3.6.   If  A  is  a  compact  Hausdorff  space,  then  the  graph  topology 

and  the  compact-open  topology  are  identical  on  ^j{k). 

Next,  we  turn  to  £,   (A).   The  first  point  to  be  noted  is  that 

■?*  (A)  is  not  necessarily  compact  but,  as  established  in  Theorem 
v^  o 

3.2,  only  completely  regular.   Nevertheless,  we  can  state  a  result  on 
which  the  importance  of  the  compact-open  topology  is  partly  based. 

Theorem  3.7.   If  A  is  a  compact  Hausdorff  space,  then  j£,  (A)  ,  endowed 
with  the  compact-open  topology  is  a  completely  regular  Hausdorff  space. 

The  question  remains  as  to  whether  the  graph  topology  has  any 
relevance  for/*(A).   A  little  reflection  leads  to  one  to  an  affirmative, 
and  somewhat  surprising,  answer.   Since  J"   (A)  is  completely  regular, 
it  can  be  embedded  in  a  compact  Hausdorff  space   n(A);  see,  for 
example,  [10,  p.  243,  paragraph  2].   Furthermore,  a  continuous  function 
from  >H_(A)  into   3/  (A)  has  a  closed  (indeed  compact)  graph  in  /l\_(k) 
x  *S   (A).   This  observation  allows  us  to  define  the  graph  topology  on 
jP    (A)  and  to  state  a  generalization  of  Theorem  3.6. 

Theorem  3.8.   If  A  is  a  compact  Hausdorff  space,  then  the  compact-open 
topology  on  aZ,   (A)  is  identical  to  the  relativization  on  ^£?  (A)  of  the 
topology  of  closed  convergence  on  nAS&)    x  "] (A) ,  where   K (A)  is  a 
compact  Hausdorff  space  in  which  j*   (A)  is  imbedded. 


-12- 

We  shall  refer  to  this  relative  topology  on  J^   (A)  as  the  induced 
graph  topology  on  J^   (A). 

4.   The  Model  and  Results 

We  now  have  all  the  technical  machinery  we  need  to  develop  the 
principal  results  of  this  paper.   We  state  a  preliminary  definition 
with  the  remark  that  a  Radon  probability  measure  on  a  topological  space 
is  to  be  understood  as  being  defined  on  the  Borel  a-algebra  generated 
by  the  topology  on  that  space. 

Definition  4.1.   A  game  on  /^(A)  is  a  Radon  probability  measure  on 
^(A),  i.e.,  an  element  of  fa\S   £?(A)). 

It  should  be  noted  that  Definition  4.1  is  not  specific  as  to  the 
topology  on  ^(A).   The  same  is  true  for  the  definition  to  follow.   It 
is  only  in  the  statement  of  our  results  that  we  shall  specify  the 
topologies  on  ^CJ(A). 

For  any  P  e   ^D(A) ,  let 

D 

M(P)  =  {a  e  B  :  V  b  e  B,  (b,a)  k   P°}. 

M(P)  thus  denotes  the  set  of  maximal  elements  in  B  for  the  preference 
relation  P  defined  on  B  x  B.  We  can  now  state  our  reformulation  of  a 
Cournot-Nash  equilibrium  distribution. 

Definition  4.2.   A  Borel  probability  measure  t  on  A  x  ^o(A)  is  a 
Cournot-Nash  equilibrium  distribution  of  a  game  y  on  ^<j.(A)  if 

(i)   the  marginal  distribution  of  t  on  ^o(A),  t  /» r  k\>    equals  y, 
(ii)  x(B  )  =  1  where  B  =  {(a,f)  e  A  x  £,  (A)  :  a  e  M(f(fA))}. 

T  X     l  A    ' 


-13- 


We  can  now  present 

Theorem  4. 1 .   If  A  is  a  compact  Hausdorff  space,  there  exists  a 
Cournot-Nash  equilbrium  distribution  of  a  game  on  ^o(A)  if_  J£  (A)  is 
endowed  with  the  graph  topology  or  equivalently  with  the  compact-open 
topology* 

Next,  we  consider  the  space  ^ct(A).   We  can  define  a  game  on 
j£    (A)  as  well  as  the  Cournot-Nash  equilibrium  distributions  of  such  a 
game  by  substituting  /C  (A)  for  x-o(A)  in  Definitions  4.1  and  4.2. 

We  can  now  state 

Theorem  4.2.   If  A  is  a  compact  Hausdorff  space,  there  exists  a 
Cournot-Nash  equilibrium  distribution  of  a  game  on  Xl  (A)  if   ^/?(A) 

1 id f  Q  —-Q 

is  endowed  with  the  induced  graph  topology  or  equivalently  with  the 
compact-open  topology. 

For  our  next  result,  we  assume  that  A  is  a  convex,  compact  subset 
of  a  topological  vector  space.   We  shall  say  that  P  z    Jn  (A  x  A)  is 
irref lexivelv  convex  if  for  any  a  e  A,  a  k   con  {b  :  (b,a)  e  P  }  where 
con  W  denotes  the  convex  hull  of  a  set  W.   For  any  B  e  ~>7  (A)  with  B 
convex,  let 

yjr°(A)  =  {P  e  ?-/  (B  x  B)  :  P  is  irref lexively  convex} 

£«(A)  =   U     ?f(B). 

B  convex 

/$  CO 

In  keeping  with  our  earlier  notation,  we  shall  let  ȣ,  (A)  denote 
the  space  of  continuous  functions  from  /^\.(A)  into   ^-  (A)  when  the 
latter  is  endowed  with  the  topology  of  closed  convergence.  jP        (A) 
denotes  the  space  of  continuous  functions  from  /rL(A)  into  a  subset  of 


-14- 

^4-    '    (A)  obtained  by  considering  sets  in  //(Ax  A)  and  with  that 
subset  endowed  with  the  order  topology. 

We  can  now  state  analogues  of  Theorems  4.1  and  4.2  to  a  setup  where 
the  payoffs  are  not  necessarily  generated  by  transitive  relations. 

Theorem  4.3.   If  A  is  a  compact  convex  subset  of  Hausdorff  topological 
vector  space,  there  exists  a  Cournot-Nash  equilibrium  distribution  of  a 
game  on  /£^     (A)  or  on   ,^   (A)  if  these  spaces  are  endowed  with  their 
induced  graph  topologies  or  equivalently  with  their  compact-open 
topologies. 

Note  that  we  have  no  result  on  the  existence  of  Cournot-Nash 
equilibria  in  games  on  Jc,     (A)  when  the  latter  is  endowed  with  the 
graph  topology.   The  reason  for  this  lies  in  the  absence  of  the 
compactness  property  of   J.  (A)  when  the  latter  is  endowed  with  the 
topology  of  closed  convergence;  see  Grodal  [15]  for  a  counter  example. 

5.   On  the  Existence  of  Maximal  Elements  in  Compact  Sets 

In  this  section  we  present  two  results  on  the  existence  of  maximal 

c 
elements  with  respect  to  P   in  a  compact  set.   These  results  constitute 

essential  ingredients  in  the  proofs  of  Theorems  4.1  and  4.2  but  since 

they  may  have  independent  interest,  we  have  collected  them  in  a  separate 

section.   It  is  worth  stating,  however,  that  the  results  themselves  are 

essentially  known  in  the  mathematical  economics  literature  and  we  detail 

this  in  the  accompanying  remarks  below. 

We  can  now  present 

Theorem  5.  1.   For  any  P  z      JT  (A)  ,  M(P)  t    <j>. 


-15- 


Corrolary  5.1.   Theorem  5.1  is  valid  for  any  P  e      •J'Ah)  C\    J-}    (A  x  A) 
* *-        B  o 

Next,  we  present  analogous  results  for  the  convex  non-transitive 


case. 


Theorem  5.2.   For  any  P  e  j-^°(k) ,    M(P)  *  <J>. 

Corrolary  5.2.   Theorem  5.2  is  valid  for  any  P  e  J   r°(a)  H  D")  (A  x  A) 


Proof  of  Theorem  5.1. 

Suppose  M(P)  =  <J)  and  let  0  =  {y  e  B  :  (x,y)  e  P  }  for  any  x  e  B. 
For  any  a  e  B,  there  exists  b  e  B  such  that  a  e  0,  .   If  not,  then  for 
all  b  e  B,  a  £   0  .   This  means  that  (b,a)  £   PC,  i.e.,  a  e  M(P)b,  a 
contradiction  to  the  emptiness  of  M(P).   Also  note  that  for  any  b  e  B, 
0, ,  being  a  projection  of  an  open  set,  is  also  open.   Hence  {0  } 

is  an  open  cover  of  B.   Since  B  is  compact,  it  has  a  finite  subcover. 
Pick  a  finite  subcover  with  the  smallest  number  of  elements  and  let 

this  number  be  k.   Hence  there  exists  b.  e  B,  i  =  1,  ...,  k  such  that 

k 
B  C  U  0b  . 
i=l    i 
Next  we  show  that  k  =  1.   Suppose  not,  i.e.,  k  is  an  integer  greater 

than  one.   Certainly  b,  £   0,  .   Then  there  exists  i  <  k  such  that 

k    \ 

b,  e  0,  .   Now  pick  any  y  e  0,  .   Then  by  complemented  transitivity  of 

i  k 

P,  y  e  0,  .   Hence  0,    CL    0,   and  we  have  contradicted  the  fact  that 
b.  b,       b. 

l  k       i 

we  had  a  smallest  subcover.   Hence  B  C  0,  .   But  this  implies  that 

bl 

b.  e  0   ,  a  final  contradiction  completes  the  proof.  II 

1 

Remark  1.   Theorem  5.1  was  first  stated  and  proved  by  Schmeidler  [32, 

Lemma  2]  for  the  case  when  X  is  a  subset  of  R  .   On  comparison,  the 

reader  will  find  that  our  proof  is  slightly  different  from  his. 


-16- 


Proof  of  Theorem  5.2. 

For  any  a  e  B,  let  T(a)  =  con  {b  e  B  :  (b,a)  e  P  }.   Suppose  there 
exists  a  e  B  such  that  T(a)  =  <J>.   Then  for  all  b  £   B,  (b,a)  e  P  ,  i.e., 
a  e  M(P)  and  the  proof  is  finished.   Thus,  assume  that  T(a)  *  §   for 
all  a  e  B. 

For  any  a  e  B,  T(a)  is  a  convex  set  by  assumption.   Now  for  any 

b  e  B,  consider  T   (b)  ■  {a  e  B  :  b  e  T(a)  }  =  con  (a  e  B  :  (b,a)  e  P° }. 

This  is  precisely  the  convex  hull  of  the  set  0,  defined  in  the  proof  of 

b 

Theorem  5.1  and  it  is  open  in  B;  see  for  example,  Lemma  5.1  in  [40]. 
(If  0,  is  empty,  the  claim  is  a  trivial  one). 

Thus  all  the  conditions  of  Browder's  fixed  point  theorem  [4]  are 
satisfied  and  there  exists  a   e  B  such  that  a   e  T(a  ),  i.e.,  a   e  con 
{b:   (b,a  )  e  P  },  an  impossibility.   Hence  we  have  contradicted  our 
assumption  that  T(a)  *  $  f°r  a^  a  e  B.   The  proof  is  finished.       II 


Remark  2.   Theorem  5.2  goes  back  to  Sonnenschein  [36]  for  the  case  when 
X  =  R  ;  also  see  Anderson  [1,  Theorem  1].   The  most  up-to-date 
reference  is  Yannelis-Prabhakar  [39]. 

6.   Proofs  of  the  Principal  Results 

Proof  of  Theorem  4.1. 

We  prove  the  theorem  for  the  case  when  /\Z(A)  is  endowed  with  the 
compact-open  topology.  The  proof  for  the  case  when  ^J(A)  is  endowed 
with  the  graph  topology  then  follows  from  Theorem  3.6. 

As  in  Mas-Colell  [29],  the  proof  is  an  application  of  the  Ky  Fan, 
Glicksberg  fixed  point  theorem  [11,14];  (also  see,  for  example,  Berge 


-17- 

[3,  p.  251]).   We  show  in  a  series  of  claims  that  all  the  conditions 
for  the  applicability  of  this  theorem  are  satisfied.   Let 

J=  |Te4i(  £(A)    x  A)  :  t  ^(A)  =  y}. 

Claim  1 :  ^J  is  nonempty. 

Since  Dirac  measures  are  in  n^(A) ,  certainly  we  are  guaranteed 
that  /Tl(A)  t    <f>.   Since  \i    e    ?K.(  3SA))  ,    we  can  now  appeal  to  Theorem 
17  in  Schwartz  [34,  p.  63]  to  assert  the  existence  of  a  unique  Radon 
measure  X  on  A  x  -£(A)    such  that 

(*)      X(B  x  C)  =  v(B)y(C)  for  all  B  e  (2>(A),    C  e  43(/£(A)). 

Note  that  Schwartz  states  (  )  in  his  theorem  in  terms  of  the  essential 
outer  measure  but  since  we  are  dealing  with  probability  measures,  the 
distinction  can  be  neglected.   The  reason  for  this  is  that  we  have 
defined  a  Radon  measure  in  terms  of  Definition  R_  of  Schwartz  [34, 
p.  13]  and  from  the  proof  of  R  =  >  R.  (Schwartz  [34,  p.  13],  we  see 
that  the  measure  of  a  set  with  finite  measure  equals  the  essential 
outer  measure  of  that  set. 
From  (  )  we  obtain 

X  A(A)(B)  =  X(A  x  B)  =  v(A>u(B)  "  y(B)  for  all  B  e  d&  (  3(A)) 

Since  X(A  x  ^.(A))  =  v(A)u(  3(A))    =    1  and  since,  by  definition, 
measures  are  non-negative,  X  e  J    and  the  proof  of  the  claim  is  complete. 


-18- 


iim  2.  +U    i 


Claim  2.  v7  is  convex. 


Pick  y  ,  y   from  J    and  X  a  real  number  such  that  0  <  X  <  1.   Then 

1  O 

it  is  routinely  checked  that  the  marginal  of  Xy  +  (l-X)y  on  ^c(A)  is 
y  and  that  Xy1  +  (l-X)y2  e  &L  (  £(A)  x  A). 


Claim  3.  ^J    is  compact. 

We  show  first  that  v_J  is  tight  (equally  interiorly  regular  or 
equally  tight  in  the  terminology  of  Schwartz  [34,  p.  379,  Definition  4]) 
Towards  this  end,  pick  any  6  >  0.   Since  y  e  M( •o  (A)),  there  exists  a 
compact  set  K  CL^c(A)    such  that  y(K)  >  1  -  6.   Since  the  marginal  of  y 
on  /C.(A)  for  any  y  e  (y  Is  p,  certainly 

Y(A  x  K)  =  Y^(A)(K>  =  M<K)  >  1-5- 

Hence  we  can  appeal  to  Theorem  3  in  [34,  p.  379]  (also  see  Topsoe  [37; 
Theorem  9.1])  to  assert  that  U    is  relatively  compact. 

All  that  remains  to  be  shown  is  that  ^J   is  closed  in  /KiA  x  *£.(A). 
To  show  this,  pick  a  net  {y  }  from  <l)  such  that  y   ■»■  y.   For  any  closed 
set  F  in  ^.(A),  we  know  by  the  Portmanteau  theorem  (Theorem  8.1  in 
[37])  that  lira  sup  y  (A  x  F)  _<  y(A  x  F) .   This  can  be  rewritten  as 

lira  sup  T^(A)(F)  <  y^(A)(F). 

Since  y  (A  x  ^£_(A))  =  1  for  all  a,  and  y(A  x  /C(A))  =  1,  we  conclude 

by  a  second  application  of  the  Portmanteau  theorem  that  Y  j>  f  k\    * 

y  ~         .   Since  ya^£(A)  =  U  f°r  a11  a'  Y^(A)  =  V   3nd  the  pr°°f  *S 
complete. 


•19- 


Remark  3.   The  proof  of  Claim  3  offered  here  is  different  from  that  in 
Khan  [22]  which  relied  on  a  lemma  of  Hof fman-Jorgenson  [18],  rather 
than  on  the  relative  compactness  of  a  tight  subset  of  a  space. 

t-r  Ax  ^  (A) 

Claim  4.   B  :   Jj  +   2  has  a  closed  graph. 

Let  t  *   x,  (a  ,f  )  +  (a,f),  and  (a  ,f  )  e  B   .   We  have  to  show 

T 

that  (a,f)  e  B  . 

v 
As  in  the  proof  of  Claim  3,  we  can  show  that  x.  ■*■   T  .   Furthermore, 

A    A 

since  f   +  f  in  the  compact-open  topology,  and  since  VK(A)  is  compact 
Hausdorff  by  Theorem  3.2,  we  can  appeal  to  the  fact  that  the  evaluation 
map  is  continuous;  see,  for  example,  Dugundji  [10,  Theorem  XII. 2. 4,  p. 
260].   Hence  fV(^)  +  f(TA>* 

Since  (aV,fV)  e  B  y,  aV  e  M(fV(t^))  and  hence  (aV,aV)  z   fV($. 

T 

Since  f  (t  )  ■*■  f(x  )  and  (a  ,a  )  ■*■   (a, a),  certainly  a  e  D  where  D  e 
A       A 

J-f(A)  is  such  that  f(x  )  e  J  (A). 

Now  suppose  a  i   M(f(x.)).   Then  there  exists  b  e  D  such  that  (b,a) 

e  (f(t  ))  .   Since  D  is  compact,  Hausdorff,  certainly  D  x  D  is  regular. 

Hence  there  exists  a  neighborhood  U  of  (b,a)  and  an  open  set  V   ZZ> 

f(xA)  such  that  U  f\  V  =  <f>.   Relying  on  the  definition  of  the  topology 

of  closed  convergence  this  means  that  there  exist  D   e  J-I(h)    such  that 

fV(x"')  e  5  <A>  and  bV  e  DV  and  v  such  (bV,aV)  e  (fV(xAV))°  for  all  v  > 

A      nv  " 

—  v   v 

v.   But  this  is  a  contradiction  to  the  fact  that  (a  ,f  )  e  B   for  all 


Claim  5.   For  any  t  e  J  ,  B  is  a  closed  set  in  J^  (A)  x  A. 
This  is  a  simple  consequence  of  Claim  4. 
Next,  we  consider  the  map  Q  :  ^J    +  2    such  that 


-20- 


Q(t)  -  {p  e  3   i    P(BT)  -  1}. 


Claim  6.   For  any  t  e  ^/    ,  Q(t)  *    <j>. 

The  proof  of  this  claim  relies  on  the  fact  that  the  Dirac  point 
measures  on  a  topological  measure  space  are  dense  in  the  space  of 
probability  measures  on  that  space.   Specifically,  Theorem  11.1  in 

Topsoe  [37,  p.  48]  assures  us  of  a  net  {y  }  converging  to  y  such  that 

v  v 

each  y   has  a  finite  support.   Pick  a  particular  y  and  assume  that  its 

support  consists  of  k  elements,  f  ,  f  ~  ,  ...,  f,  .   From  Theorem  5.1,  we 

know  that  M(f.(x.))  *   4>.   Let  as    e  M(f.(x.)).   Certainly  (a.,f.)  e  A  x 
l   A  iiA  l   i 

z£(A).   Now  for  any  W  e  &  (A)  x  <2>  (  -£(A))  let 

6V1  (W)  =  1  if  (aj[,fi)  e  W 
=  0  otherwise. 

It  is  easy  to  see  that  5  "  e  t^KA  x  ^(A)).   Since  {(a.,f.)|  is 
a  compact  set  in  A  x  /O  (A)  ,  for  any  W  e  C£>(A)  x  ®  C^^(A))  and  for 
any  £  >  0,  certainly  6   ({a,f.})  >  6   (W)  -e.   Now  define,  for  any 
W  e  (S(A)  x  ®  (  ^(A)), 

k 
6V(W)  =  Z      5V1(W)yV(f.). 
i=l  X 

Again,  it  is  clear  that  6   E  &\_(A  x  ^.(A)). 

We  now  show  that  the  marginal  of  6  on  ^o(A)  is  y  .   Pick  any 
F  e  $>(  £(A)).   Then 


k 
5V^(A)(F)  =  6V(A  x  F)  =  I    5V1(A  x  F)yV(f.) 


-21- 


=  Z     yV(f.)  where  I  =  {i  e  (l...k)  :  f.  e  F} 
,  _     i  l  1    J 

lei 


=  „V(F>. 

We  can  also  show  that  5  (B  )  =  1.   To  see  this,  simply  note  that 
k  T 

l){a.,f.}  is  a  compact  set  and  this  is  contained  in  B  . 
i  =  l  v  £  T 

Next  consider  the  marginal  of  5  on  A.   Since  /TV (A)  is  compact 

by  virtue  of  [38,  p.  76]  (also  [34,  p.  379]),  there  exists  a  subnet  6 

such  that  67  converges  to  a  limit  a  in  )v\.(A). 
A 

Given  that  /O  (A)  is  completely  regular  by  virtue  of  Theorem  3.5, 
and  that  A,  being  compact  Hausdorff,  is  also  completely  regular,  we  can 

appeal  to  Dugundj i  [10;  Theorem  VII.  7.2,  p.  15A]  to  assert  that  A  x 

(A)  is  completely  regular.   We  can  now  apply  Lemma  5.1  in  Hoffman- 

Jorgenson  [18]  to  assert  the  existence  of  a  measure  6   e  /7V(A  x  'O(A)) 

such  that  6.  =  a  and  5  /*  ( \\   =    M  ana*  such  that  5   ■*  <T. 

Since  B  is  a  closed  set  by  virtue  of  Claim  4,  we  can  appeal  to 

T 

the  Portmanteau  theorem  in  [37]  to  assert  that  5  (B  )  >  lira  sup  5  (B  ) 

t  —  T 

=  1.   Since  5*(A  x  ^(A))  =  y(^(A))  =  1,  6*(B  )  =  1.   Hence  5*  e 
Q(t)  and  the  proof  of  the  claim  is  complete. 

Claim  8.   Q  is  an  upper  hemicontinuous  correspondence. 

Since  ^j     is  compact,  it  suffices  to  show  that  Q  has  a  closed  graph 
(see  Berge  [3,  p.  112,  Corollary]).   Towards  this  end,  let  t   +  t, 

V      /  Vx         V 

p   e  Q(t  )  and  p   +  p.   We  have  to  show  that  p(B  )  =  1.   Since  p  is  a 
Radon  measure,  it  suffices  to  show  that  p(K)  =  0  for  all  compact  K  d. 
B  .   By  Claim  4,  we  know  that  lim  sup  B    C  B  .   Hence  K  cC  (lim  sup 

T 

B   )  .   From  Klein-Thompson  [26;  Proposition  3.2.11],  we  obtain 

T 


•22- 


k  d  ( n  vj  b  Y>  -     o  (  lj  b  >' 

ctY>a   T  a    Y  >  <*   t 


where  A  denotes  the  closure  of  A.   Since  K  is  compact,  every  open  cover 
has  a  finite  subcover.   Hence  there  exists  a'  such  that 


K  d.    (  VJ   B  J 

Y  >  a*   tT 


By   the   raonotonicity   property   of    a  measure 


p(K)    <p((     \J      B      ) 
Y   >    a*       tY 


and  by  the  Portmanteau  theorem  [38]  we  obtain 


p(K)  <  lira  inf  p  (K)  <   lira  inf  p  ((  l^J   B   )  ) 

Y  >    a'       xY 


Now    for    any    v  >    a' 


.c 


B        CZ.     I       1      B        which   implies   B         "T2   (      LJ      B      ) 
t  y  >   a1      t  '  t  y  >    a'      t 


Hence,    by    the   monotonicity   property   of   a  measure, 


cv     _      v,_c 


P    ((      \^J     B      )    )   £  p   (B      )    =   0 

>t 
ax  T 


The  proof  of  the  claim  in  finished. 


-23- 


Remark  4.   The  proof  presented  here  is  a  simplification  of  the  one 
presented  for  an  analogous  claim  in  [22]. 

We  can  now  apply  the  Ky  Fan,  Glicksberg  fixed  point  theorem  (see, 
for  example,  Berge  [3,  p.  251])  to  the  map  Q  to  complete  the  proof  of 
the  theorem. 

Remark  5.   We  have  provided  the  proof  of  Theorem  4.1  with  /^r  (A) 
endowed  with  the  compact-open  topology.   In  particular,  we  used  in  the 
proof  of  Claim  4,  the  fact  that  the  evaluation  map  <h\.{k)    x  £  (A)  ■*■ 
jf(A)  is  continuous.   If,  instead,  we  had  considered  the  case  where 

^.(A)  is  endowed  with  the  graph  topology,  a  direct  proof  is  available. 

v  v 

As  in  the  proof  of  Claim  3,  let  x   +  x  and  f   +  f  in  the  graph  topology 

A      A 

on  /£(A).   We  shall  show  £V(tVk)+   f(xA). 

A      A 

Since  the  net  (x.,f  (t.))  lies  in  a  compact  set,  we  can  find  a 

a  A 

subnet,  also  indexed  by  v,  such  that  (x  ,f  (t  ))  converges  to  (x  ,b) 

A       A  A 

where  b  e  3"(A).   Since  (t)\fV(x^))  e  Gr(fV),  and  since  Gr(fV)  +Gr(f), 

A       A 

we  obtain  that  (x,,b)  e  Gr(f).   But  f  is  a  function  and  hence  b  =  f(x.). 
A  A 

Proof  of  Theorem  4.2.   The  proof  is  identical  to  that  of  the  proof  of 
Theorem  4.1  except  for  the  fact  that  we  appeal  to  Theorem  3.8  to  show 
the  equivalence  between  the  compact-open  topology  and  the  induced 
graph  topology  on  j£  (A).  II 

Proof  of  Theorem  4.3.   Again,  we  follow  the  proofs  of  Theorems  4.1  and 
4.2  but  with  Theorem  5.2  substituted  for  Theorem  5.1  in  the  proof  of 
Claim  6.  II 

7.   Proofs  of  Results  in  Section  3 
We  begin  with  a 


-24- 


Proof  of  Theorem  3.1.   It  is  well  known  that  the  space  of  closed 

subsets  of  a  locally  compact  space  endowed  with  the  topology  of  closed 

convergence  is  compact;  see,  for  example,  Problem  3  in  [17].   Hence, 

we  have  to  show  that   ^(A)  is  a  closed  subset  of  J-/(A  x  A).   Towards 

this  end,  pick  a  net  (P  }  from  3-  (A)  such  that  P  ■*■   P.   We  have  to 

1  v J  v 

show  P  e   ^(A).   Let  B   e  y\  (A)  such  that  P   e    *£      (A).   Since 

V  V        v/  d 

V 

J-"|(A)  is  compact,  Hausdorff,  there  exists  a  subnet,  also  indexed 

by  v,  such  that  B   ■>  B.   We  shall  show  that  P  e   3\,(A). 
v  B 

We  first  show  that  P  is  an  element  of  -H(BxB)  and  is  reflexive. 
Since  A  is  compact,  certainly  B  #  <J>.   Pick  any  (a,b)  e  P.   There  exists 

(a  ,b  )  e  P   for  each  v  such  that  (a  ,b  )  -*■  (a,b).   Since  a  ,b   e  B  , 
v  v 

(a,b)  BxB,  and  hence  P  C  BxB.   Pick  any  b  e  B.   By  the  definition  of 

closed  convergence,  we  can  construct  a  subnet  IB  }  of  JB  }  and  b   e 
°    '  l  a '  L  v '  a 

B   such  that  b   +  b.   Since  P   e  v7B  (A),  certainly  (b  ,b  )  e  P  . 
a  a  o  o  ooo 

Since  P   ■>  P,  again  by  the  definition  of  closed  convergence,  (b,b)  e   P. 

Next,  we  show  that  P  is  complementedly  transitive.   In  what 

follows,  we  shall  take  complements  of  P  and  P   in  BxB  and 

B  xB   respectively.   Suppose  (a,b)  e  P  ,  (b,c)  e  P   but  (a,c)  £   P  . 

Since  (a,c)  e  P  and  P   +  P,  there  exists  (a  ,c  )  e  P   such  that  (a  , 

v  v 

V\     /  V  V 

c  )  +  (a,c).   Since  B  +   B,  there  exists  b   e  B   such  that  b   ■*  b. 

v  v 

Hence  (a  ,b  )  ■»■  (a,b)  and  (b  ,c  )  +  (b,c).   By  [12,  Proposition  3.1], 

there   exists  v  such  that  (a  ,b  )  £   P   and  (b  ,c  )  Jt   P   for  all  v  >  v. 

v  v 

V   Vs  V   vx 

This  implies  (a  ,c  )  t   P   or  that  (a  ,c  )  e  P  ,  a  contradiction. 

V    .  V 

The  proof  of  the  theorem  is  complete.  II 

Proof  of  Theorem  3.2.   See  the  proof  of  Theorem  2  in  Khan-Sun  [24].   II 
Proof  of  Theorem  3.3.   See  the  proof  of  Theorem  1  in  Khan-Sun  [24].   II 


-25- 

Proof  of  Theorem  3.4.   See,  for  example,  the  Notes  to  Section  11  in 
Topsoe  [37,  p.  76].   Also  Schwartz  [34,  p.  379].  II 

Proof  of  Theorem  3.5.   Since  /H(A)  is  compact  Hausdorff  by  virtue  of 
Theorem  3.4  and  since  J-  (A)  endowed  with  the  topology  of  closed 
convergence  is  compact  by  virtue  of  Theorem  3.1,  /^,(A)  endowed  with 
the  graph  topology  is  a  subspace  of  a  compact  Hausdorff  space.   Hence 
it  is  normal  and  therefore  completely  regular  and  Hausdorff.   Since  a 
subspace  of  a  completely  regular  Hausdorff  space  is  completely  regular 
and  Hausdorff  (see,  for  example,  [10,  VII. 7. 2(1)],  we  are  done.       II 

Proof  of  Theorem  3.6.   Since  A  is  compact  Hausdorff,  v^V(A)  is  compact 
Hausdorff  by  Theorem  3.4.   Furthermore,  jr(A),  endowed  with  the 
topology  of  closed  convergence,  is  compact  Hausdorff  by  Theorem  3.1. 
We  can  now  apply  Corollary  1  in  Khan-Sun  [23].  II 

Proof  of  Theorem  3.7.   Since  the  range  of  an  element  in  ^*,    (A)  is  a 
^o 

completely  regular  Hausdorff  space  by  virtue  of  Theorem  3.3, 

the  claim  is  a  direct  consequence  of  Nagata  [31,  Theorem  F,  p.  272].  II 

Proof  of  Theorem  3.8.   See  the  proof  of  Corollary  2  in  Khan-Sun  [23].  II 


-26- 


Ref erences 

[1]   Anderson,  R.  M. ,  "Core  Theory  with  Strongly  Convex  Preferences," 
Econometrica  40  (1981)  1457-1468. 

[2]   Back,  K. ,  "Concepts  of  Similarity  for  Utility  Functions,"  Journal 
of  Mathematical  Economics  15  (1986)  129-142. 

[3]   Berge,  C.  ,  Topological  Spaces,  Oliver  and  Boyd,  Edinburgh,  1963. 

[4]   Browder  F. ,  "The  Fixed  Point  Theory  of  Multi-Valued  Mappings  in 
Topological  Vector  Spaces,"  Mathematische  Annalen,  177  (1968) 
283-301. 

[5]   Chichilnisky ,  G. ,  "Spaces  of  Economic  Agents,"  Journal  of 
Economic  Theory  15  (1977)  160-173. 

[6]   Choquet,  G. ,  "Convergences,"  Annales  Universite  de  Grenoble  23 
(1947-48)  55-112. 

[7]   Cournot,  A.  A.,  Recherches  sur  les  Principles  Mathematiques  de  la 
Theorie  des  Richesses,  Librarie  des  Sciences  Politiques  et 
Sociales,  Paris,  1838.   Also  translation  by  Nathaniel  Bacon 
(1897),  Macraillan,  New  York. 

[8]   Debreu,  G. ,  "A  Social  Equilibrium  Existence  Theorem,"  Proceedings 
of  the  National  Academy  of  Sciences  U.S.A.  38  (1952)  886-893. 

[9]   Debreu,  G. ,  "Neighboring  Economic  Agents,"  in  La  Decision, 

Editions  du  Centre  National  de  la  Recherche  Scientif ique,  Paris, 
1969. 

[10]   Dugundji,  J.,  Topology,  Allyn  and  Bacon  Inc.,  Boston,  1966. 

[11]   Fan,  Ky,  "Fixed  Points  and  Minimax  Theorems  in  Locally  Convex 

Linear  Spaces,"  Proceedings  of  the  National  Academy  of  Sciences, 
U.S.A.  38  (1952)  121-126. 

[12]   Frolik,  Z. ,  "Concerning  Topological  Convergence  of  Sets," 
Czechoslovak  Mathematics  Journal  85  (1960)  168-179. 

[13]   Gale,  D.  and  A.  Mas-Colell,  "An  Equilibrium  Existence  Theorem 
for  a  General  Model  Without  Ordered  Preferences,"  Journal  of 
Mathematical  Economics  2  (1974)  9-15.   Erratum  in  ibid.,  G(1978) 
297-298. 

[14]   Glicksberg,  I.,  "A  Further  Generalization  of  the  Kakutani  Fixed 
Point  Theorem  with  Applications  to  Nash  Equilibrium  Points, 
Proceedings  of  the  American  Mathematical  Society  3  (1952)  170-174, 


-27- 


[15]   Grodal,  B. ,  "A  Note  on  the  Space  of  Preference  Relations," 
Journal  of  Mathematical  Economics  13  (1975)  289-294. 

[16]   Hildenbrand,  W. ,  "On  Economies  with  Many  Agents,  Journal  of 
Economic  Theory  2  (1970)  161-188. 

[17]   Hildenbrand,  W. ,  Core  and  Equilbria  of  a  Large  Economy,  Princeton 
University  Press,  Princeton,  1974. 

[18]   Hof fman-Jorgenson,  J.,  Probability  in  B-spaces  Lecture  Notes 
Series  No.  48,  Aarhus  Universitet,  Aarhus ,  1977. 

[19]   Kannai ,  Y. ,  "Continuity  Properties  of  the  Core  of  a  Market," 

Econometrica  38  (1970)  791-815.   A  correction  in  ibid,  40  (1972) 
955-958. 

[20]   Khan,  M.  Ali,  "On  Extensions  of  the  Cournot-Nash  Theorem,"  in 
Advances  in  Economic  Theory,  C.  D.  Aliprantis  et  al.  (eds.), 
Lecture  Notes  in  Economics  and  Mathematical  Systems,  Vol.  244, 
1985. 

[21]   Khan,  M.  Ali  and  N.  Papageorgiou,  "On  Cournot-Nash  Equilibria  in 
Generalized  Qualitative  Games  with  an  Atomless  Measure  Space  of 
Agents,"  Proceedings  of  the  American  Mathematical  Society, 
forthcoming. 

[22]   Khan,  M.  Ali,  "On  a  Variant  of  a  Theorem  of  Schmeidler,"  B.E.B.R. 
Working  Paper  No.  1130,  Revised  in  December  1986. 

[23]   Khan,  M.  Ali  and  Y.  Sun,  "On  a  Graph  Topology  on  C(X,Y)  with  X 

Compact  Hausdorff  and  Y  Tychonoff,"  University  of  Illinois,  mimeo. 

[24]   Khan,  M.  Ali  and  Y.  Sun,  "On  Complete  Regularity  of  Space  of 

Economic  Agents  Endowed  with  the  Order  Topology,"  University  of 
Illinois,  mimeo. 

[25]   Kim,  T. ,  K.  Prikry  and  N.  Yannelis,  "Equilibria  in  Abstract 

Economies  with  a  Measure  Space  of  Agents  and  with  an  Infinite 
Dimensional  Strategy  Space,"  Journal  of  Approximation  Theory, 
forthcoming. 

[26]   Klein,  E.  and  A.  C.  Thompson,  Theory  of  Correspondences,  John 
Wiley  and  Sons,  New  York,  1984. 

[27]   Kuratowski,  K. ,  Topology,  Academic  Press,  New  York,  1966. 

[28]   Mas-Colell,  A.,  "An  Equilibrium  Existence  Theorem  Without  Complete 
or  Transitive  Preferences,"  Journal  of  Mathematical  Economics  1 
(1974)  237-246. 


-28- 


[29]   Mas-Colell,  A.,  "On  a  Theorem  of  Schmeidler ,"  Journal  of 
Mathematical  Economics  13  (1984)  201-206. 

[30]   Nash,  J.  F. ,  "Equilibrium  Points  in  N-Person  Games,"  Proceedings 
of  the  National  Academy  of  Sciences,  U.S.A.  38  (1950)  48-49. 

[31]   Nagata,  J.,  Modern  General  Topology,  North  Holland  Publishing  Co., 
Amsterdam,  1968. 

[32]   Schmeidler,  D. ,  "Competitive  Equilibria  in  Markets  with  a 

Continuum  of  Traders  and  Incomplete  Preferences,"  Econometrica  37 
(1969)  578-585. 

[33]  Schmeidler,  D. ,  "Equilibrium  Points  of  Non-Atomic  Games,"  Journal 
of  Statistical  Physics  7  (1973)  295-300. 

[34]   Schwartz,  L. ,  Radon  Measures  on  Arbitrary  Topological  Spaces, 
Oxford  University  Press,  Bombay,  1973. 

[35]   Shafer,  W.  and  H.  Sonnenschein,  "Equilibrium  in  Abstract 

Economics  Without  Ordered  Preferences,"  Journal  of  Mathematical 
Economics  2  (1975)  345-348. 

[36]   Sonnenschein,  H. ,  "Demand  Theory  Without  Transitive  Preferences 
with  Applications  to  the  Theory  of  Competitive  Equilibrium,"  in 
Preferences,  Utility  and  Demand,  J.  Chipman  et.  al.  (eds.) 
Harcourt  Brace  Jovanovich  Inc.,  New  York,  1971. 

[37]   Topsoe,  F. ,  Topology  and  Measure,  Lecture  Notes  in  Mathematics 
No.  133,  Springer-Verlag,  New  York,  1970. 

[38]   Yannelis,  N. ,  "Equilibrium  in  Non-Cooperative  Models  of 
Competition,"  Journal  of  Economic  Theory,  forthcoming. 

[39]  Yannelis,  N.  and  N.  Prabhakar,  "Existence  of  Maximal  Elements  and 
Equilibria  in  Linear  Topological  Spaces,"  Journal  of  Mathematical 
Economics  12  (1983)  233-245. 


D/131 


HECKMAN 

BINDERY  INC. 

DEC  95 


N  MANCHESTER,1 
INDIANA  469r