Skip to main content

Full text of "The Organon, or Logical treatises, of Aristotle. With introduction of Porphyry. Literally translated, with notes, syllogistic examples, analysis, and introduction. By Octavius Freire Owen"

See other formats


I 


■in 


1 


HANDBOUND 
AT  THE 

«afa. 


UNIVERSITY  OF 
TORONTO  PRESS 


I 


V-.r-.__ 


BOHN'S  CLASSICAL  LIBRARY. 


THE 


ORGANON,  OR  LOGICAL  TREATISES, 


ARISTOTLE 


THE 


ORGANON,  OR  LOGICAL  TREATISES, 


ARISTOTLE. 


WITH 


l1 


THE  INTRODUCTION  OF  PORPHYRY, 


LITERALLY  TRANSLATED,  WITH  NOTES,  SYLLOGISTIC  EXAMPI  ES, 
ANALYSIS,  AND  INTRODUCTION. 


BY 

OCTAVITJS  FREIRE  OWEN,  M.  A. 

OF    CHRIST   CHURCH,    OXFORD.      RECTOR   OF    BURSTOW,    SURREY;     ASD 
DOMESTIC    CHAPLAIN    TO   THE    DUKE   OF    PORTLAND. 


IN  TWO  VOLUMES. 
VOL.  I. 


LONDON:  GEORGE  BELL  &  SONS,   YOKE  STKELT, 
COVENT  .GAUDtN. 
18H0. 

NOV  -  7  1988 

DAI- 


LONDON : 

PRINTED   BY    WILLIAM   CLOWES   AND  SONS,    LIMITED, 
STAJIFOUD   STKEBT  AND  CHARING    CKOSS. 


6 

VI 


INTRODUCTION. 


The  investigation  of  the  science  of  Mind,  especially 
as  to  its  element,  Thought,  is  of  so  interesting  a  charac- 
ter as  in  great  measure  to  reconcile  the  inquirer  to  the 
abstruseness  of  formal  reasoning.  The  beauty  of  the 
flower,  whilst  concealing  the  ruggedness,  is  apt  to  with- 
draw our  attention  from  the  utility,  of  the  soil  on 
which  it  grows  ;  and  thus  in  like  manner  the  charms  of 
Idealism,  ending  but  too  frequently  in  visionary  specu- 
lation, have  obstructed  the  clear  appreciation  of  the 
design  and  use  of  Logic.  Not  that  we  deny  the  con- 
nexion which  must  ever  subsist  between  Logic,  as  the 
science  of  the  laws  of  reasoning,  and  psychology ;  in-  ^/ 
deed  the  latter  is  constantly  introduced  in  several  topics 
of  the  Organon ;  but  if  we  would  derive  real  practical 
benefit  from  logical  study,  we  must  regard  it  as  enun- 
ciative  of  the  universal  principle  of  inference,  affording 
a  direct  test  for  the  detection  of  fallacy,  and  the  estab- 
lishment of  true  conclusion. 


IV  INTRODUCTION. 

Wherefore,  while  primarily  connected  with  the  laws 
of  Thought,  Logic  is  secondarily  and  practically  allied 
to  language  as  enunciative  of  Thought.  To  enter  into 
the  mental  processes  incident  thereto,  though  so  tempt- 
ing a  theme  as  already  to  have  seduced  many  from  the 
direct  subject  of  the  science,  would  far  exceed  the 
limits  of  this  Introduction.  We  shall  therefore  content 
ourselves  with  a  few  observations  upon  the  utility  of 
the  study  connected  with  the  Organon  itself. 

It  is  a  quaint  remark  of  Erasmus,  that  the  human  un- 
derstanding, like  a  drunken  clown  lifted  on  horseback, 
falls  over  on  the  farther  side  the  instant  he  is  supported 
on  the  nearer  ;  and  this  is  the  characteristic  of  human 
praise  and  censure.  From  an  ignorant  and  exaggerated 
notion  of  its  purport,  Logic,  instead  of  being  limited  to 
its  proper  sphere,  was  supposed  commensurate  with  the 
whole  investigation  of  abstract  truth  in  relation  to 
matter,  cause,  and  entity, — in  fact,  the  substance  of  a 
folio  volume,  describing  every  phase  of  human  life, 
compressed  into  a  few  pages  of  Boethius  and  Aldrich. 
Thus,  not  having  effected  what  nothing  short  of  a  mi- 
raculous expansion  of  the  understanding  could  effect,  it 
sunk  into  insignificance,  until  recently  vindicated,  and 
placed  upon  its  proper  footing,  by  Whately,  Mansel, 
and  others. 

It  is  true  that,  whether  viewed  as  an  art  or  a  science, 


INTRODUCTION.  v 

Logic  does  not  solve  the  origin  of  mental  conception; 
but  it  furnishes  the  rules  on  which  all  reasoning  is 
constructed ;  and  it  would  be  strange  indeed  if  we  re- 
fused the  practical  assistance  of  surgery  because  it  does 
not  exhibit  in  theory  the  operation  of  will  upon  matter. 
We  may  learn  Logic  and  yet  not  be  able  to  think ;  but 
the  science  cannot  be  blamed  for  the  imperfection  of 
the  element  worked  upon,  any  more  than  the  artificer 
for  the  inferiority  of  the  only  material  within  his  reach. 
It  is  sufficient  that  Logic,  without  entering  into  all  the 
phenomena  of  mind,  provides  certain  forms  which  an 
argument,  to  be  legitimate,  must  exhibit,  certain  tests 
by  which  fallacy  may  be  detected,  and  certain  barriers 
against  ambiguity  in  the  use  of  language. 

Hence,  the  utility  of  a  science  which  enables  men 
to  take  cognizance  of  the  travellers  on  the  mind's 
highway,  and  excludes  those  disorderly  interlopers 
verbal  fallacies,  needs  but  small  attestation.  Its  search- 
ing penetration  by  definition  alone,  before  which  even 
mathematical  precision  fails,1  would  especially  com- 
mend it  to  those  whom  the  abstruseness  of  the  study 
does  not  terrify,  and  who  recognise  the  valuable  results 
which  must  attend  discipline  of  mind.  Like  a  medi- 
cine, though  not  a  panacea  for  every  ill,  it  has  the 
health  of  the  mind  for  its  aim,  but  requires  the  de- 
termination of  a  powerful  will  to  imbibe  its  nauseating 

'  Prior  Analyt.  ii.  16. 


VI  QTTROI'UCTION. 

vet  wholesome  influence :  it  is  no  wonder  therefore  that 
punv  intellects,  like  weak  stomachs,  abhor  and  reject 
it.  What  florid  declaimer  can  endure  that  the  lux- 
uriant boughs  of  verdant  sophistry,  the  rich  blossoms 
of  oratorical  fervour,  should  be  lopped  and  pared  by 
the  stern  axe  of  a  syllogism,  and  the  poor  stripped 
trunk  of  worthless  fallacy  exposed  unprotected  to  the 
nipping  atmosphere  of  truth  ? 

Like  the  science  of  which  it  treats,  not  only  has  the 
term  "  Logic  "  been  variously  applied,1  but  even  the  Or- 
ganon, as  a  whole,  presents  no  great  claim  to  unity. 
The  term  is  neither  found,  as  belonging  to  an  art 
or  science,  in  Aristotle,  nor  does  it  occur  in  the  writings 
of  Plato,  and  the  appellation  "  Organon,"  given  to  the 
treatises  before  us,  has  been  attributed  to  the  Peripatetics, 
who  maintained  against  the  Stoics  that  Logic  was  "  an 
instrument  "  of  Philosophy.  The  book,  according  to 
M.  St.  Hilaire,  was  not  called  "  Organon  "  before  the 
15th  century,2  and  the  treatises  were  collected  into  one 
volume,  as  is  supposed,  about  the  time  of  Andronicus  of 
Rhodes  ;  it  was  translated  into  Latin  by  Boethius  about 
the  6th  century.  That  Aristotle  did  not  compose  the 
Organon  as  a  whole,  is  evident  from  several  portions 
having  been  severally  regarded  as  logical,  gram- 
matical, and  metaphysical,  and  even  the  Aristotelian 
names  themselves,  Analytic  and  Dialectic,  are  applica- 
1  Scotus  super  Univ.  Qu.  3.  2  Cf.  Waitz,  vol.  ii.  p.  294. 


INTRODUCTION.  vii 

ble  only  to  certain  portions  of  the  Organon.  Still  the 
system  is  so  far  coherent  in  the  immediate  view  taken 
of  Logic,  as  conversant  with  language  in  the  process  of 
reasoning,  that  any  addition  to  the  structure  of  the 
Stagirite  can  never  augment  the  compactness  with 
which  the  syllogism,  as  a  foundation,  is  built.  The 
treatises  themselves  are  mentioned  under  distinct  titles 
by  their  author,  and  subsequent  commentators  have 
discussed  the  work,  not  as  a  whole,  but  according  to  its 
several  divisions.  It  is  remarkable  also,  that  no  quot- 
ations from  the  Categories,  de  Interpretatione,  or  So- 
phistical Elenchi,  are  found  in  the  extant  writings  of 
Aristotle,  since  those  given  by  Hitter  l  of  the  first  and 
last  must  be  considered  doubtful. 

In  the  present  Translation  my  utmost  endeavour  hus 
been  to  represent  the  mind  and  meaning  of  the  author 
as  closely  as  the  genius  of  the  two  languages  admits. 
The  benefit  of  the  student  has  been  my  especial  ob^eci; 
hence  in  the  Analysis,  the  definitions  are  given  in  the 
very  words  of  Aristotle,  and  the  syllogistic  examples, 
introduced  by  Taylor,  have  been  carefully  examined 
and  corrected.  In  order  also  to  interpret  the  more  con- 
fused passages,  I  have  departed  somewhat  from  tht 
usual  plan,  and  in  addition  to  foot-notes  have  affixec 
explanations  in  the  margin,  that  the  eye  may  catch,  ix 
the  same  line,  the    word   and  its  import.      Whereve) 

•  Vol.  iii.  p.  28. 


Vlll  INTRODUCTION. 

further  elucidation  was  necessary,  I  have  referred  to 
standard  authorities,  amongst  whom  I  would  gratefully 
commemorate  the  works  of  Mr.  Mansel  and  Dr. 
Whately,  not  forgetting  my  solitary  predecessor  in  this 
laborious  undertaking,  Thomas  Taylor,  whose  strict 
integrity  in  endeavouring  to  give  the  meaning  of  the 
text  deserves  the  highest  commendation.  For  books 
placed  at  my  disposal  I  have  especially  to  express  my 
sincere  acknowledgments  to  the  Rev.  Dr.  Hessey, 
Head  Master  of  Merchant  Tailors'  School,  and  John 
Cuninghame,  Esq.  of  Lainshaw. 

By  an  alteration  in  the  original  plan,  it  has  been 
found  requisite,  in  order  to  equalize  the  size  of  the 
volumes,  to  place  Porphyry's  Introduction  at  the  dose, 
instead  of  at  the  commencement,  of  the  Organon. 

O.  F.  O. 

£>n^ttow,  Jane  £3,  1853. 


\% 


ERRATA. 

r<ige  219,  line  2,  in  head  of  chapter  xvii.,  for  an  account  read  on  account 

—  273,  in  marginal  note  4,  for  Instance  of  a  syllogistic  argument  read 

Instance  of  asyllogistic  argument,  i.  e.  not  syllogistic 

—  594,  at  head  of  chapter  xxv.,  for  from  what  is  simply  read  fron. 

what  is  not  simply 


ARISTOTLE'S  OKGANON. 


THE  CATEGORIES.1 

Chap.  I. — Of  Homonyms,"1  Synonyms,  Paronyms. 

Things  are  termed  homonymous,  of  which  the   *■  ^at  "» 
name  alone  is  common,  but  the  definition  (of  sub- 
stance  according   to   the  name)   is  different ;   thus   "  man " 

1  Categories,  or  Predicaments,  so  called  because  they  concern  things 
•which  may  always  be  predicated,  are  the  several  classes  under  which  all 
abstract  ideas,  and  their  signs,  common  words,  may  be  arranged.  Their 
classification  under  ten  heads  was  introduced  by  Archytas  and  adopted  by 
Aristotle.  The  reason  why,  in  this  treatise  about  them,  Aristotle  does  not 
begin  from  these,  but  from  Homonyms,  &c,  is  that  he  might  previously 
explain  what  was  necessary  to  the  doctrine  of  the  Categories  to  prevenl 
subsequent  digression.  Vide  Porphyr.  in  Praedicam.  After  comparing 
various  opinions  of  Alexander  Aphrodisiensis,  Syrianus,  Simplicius,  and 
others,  it  appears  agreed  by  all,  that  Aristotle's  intention  in  this  treatise 
was,  to  discuss  simple  primary  and  general  words,  so  far  as  tin;/  are  sig- 
nificant of  things ;  at  the  same  time  to  instruct  us  in  things  and  conceptions, 
so  far  as  they  are  signified  by  icords.  A  recollection  of  this  digested  ■  t- 
planation,  will  much  assist  the  student  in  the  enunciation  of  the  plan. 

2  "  Homonyms,"  equivocal  words,--  ■"  Synonyms,"  uiiivocal,— "  Paro- 
nyms," derivative.  We  may  remark  here,  that  analogous  nouns  o 
trite  only  one  species  of  equivocal :  that  the  synonyms  of  Aristotle  musl 
be  distinguished  from  the  modern  synonyms,  which  latter  are  defined  by 
Boethius,  "those  which  have  many  names,  but  one  definition;"  and 
lastly,  that  paronyms  have  been  limited  by  the  schoolmen  to  certain  con- 
crete adjectives,  a  limitation  which  is  not  warranted  by  Aristotle,  and  is 
expressly  rejected  bv  his  Greek  commentators.— Mansel's  Rudiments  oi 
Logic.  See  also  Simplicius  Scholia,  p.  43,  b.  5.  "The  reason,  '  says 
Syrianus,  "why  things  polyonomous,  and  heteronomous,  are  omitted  I 
Aristotle,  is  because  they  rather  pertain  to  ornament  of  diction,  than  to 
the  consideration  of  things ;  they  are  therefore  more  properly  discussed 
in  the  Rhetoric  and  Poetics." 


2  aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  u. 

and   "  the  picture  of  a   man "   are   each  termed   "  animal," 
since  of  these,  the  name  alone  is  common,  but  the  definition 
(of  the  substance  according  to  the  name)  is  different : '  as  if 
any  one  were  to  assign  what  was  in  either,  to  constitute  it 
"  animal,"  he  would  allege  the  peculiar  definition  of  each. 
But  those  are  called  synonyms,  of  which  both  the 
syiwnymsT'     narae  is  common,  and  the  definition  (of  the  sub- 
stance according  to  the  name)  is  the  same,2  as 
both  "  a  man  "  and  "  an  ox  "  are  "  animal,"  for  each  of  these 
is  predicated  of  as  "  animal "  by  a  common  name,  and  the 
definition  of  the  substance  is  the  same,  since  if  a  man  gave 
the  reason  of  each  as  to  what  was  in  either,  to  constitute 
.  „  it  "  animal,"  he  would  assign  the  same  reason. 

3.  Paronyms.  .  .    '  &  . 

Again,  things  are  called  paronyms  which,  though 
differing  in  case,  have  their  appellation  (according  to  name) 
from  some  thing,  as  "  a  grammarian  "  is  called  so  from  "gram- 
mar," and  "  a  courageous  man  "  from  "  courage." 


Chap.  II.  —  Of  the  logical  division  of  Things  and  their  Attributes} 

1  Subjects  of     Op  tilings  discoursed  upon,  some  are  enunciated 
discourse  com-   after  a  complex,  others  after  an  incomplex,  man- 

plex  and  in-  .-i  i  »  ., 

Complex.  ner  »  the  complex  as  "  a  man  runs,    "  a  man  con- 

quers," but    the    incomplex    as   "  man,"    "  ox," 

1  Taylor  translates  \6yog  sometimes  "  reason,"  at  others  "  definition." 
It  is  better  to  preserve  the  latter  as  far  as  may  be,  though  the  student  will 
do  well  to  remember  that  it  is  capable  of  both  significations.  The  brack- 
ets are  retained  from  the  Leipsic  and  other  copies. 

2  Ovaia,  "  a  thing  sufficient  of  itself  to  its  own  subsistence."  Taylor. 
He  translates  it  "  essence,"  rather  than  "  substance,"  because  this  latter 
word  conveys  no  idea  of  self-subsistence.  See  his  Introduction  of  Por- 
phyry. It  must  be  observed,  however,  that  whilst  by  continued  abstrac- 
tion from  the  subject  and  different  predicates  of  Propositions,  the  predi- 
cates arrive  at  the  nine  other  categories,  the  subject  will  ultimately  end  in 
"  substance."     Cf.  Phys.  Ausc.  lib.  iii. 

3  This  chapter,  containing  the  several  divisions  of  terms,  into  abso- 
lute and  connotative,  abstract  and  concrete,  respectively,  has  presented 
endless  difficulties  to  commentators ;  and  the  question  of  relation  seems 
as  far  from  being  settled  as  ever.  The  whole  subject  may  perhaps  be 
properly  condensed  in  the  following  manner.  All  bvra  are  divided  by 
Aristotle  into  four  classes,  Universal  and  Singular  Substances,  and  Uni- 
versal and  Singular  Attributes;  the  former  existing  per  se,  the  latter  in 
the   former.     Universals  are  predicable  of  singulars,   but  attributes,  in 


CIIAl*.  II. 1 


THE    CATEGORIES. 


"  runs,"  "  conquers."     Likewise  also  some  things   2.  varieties  of 
are  predicated  of  a  certain  subject,  yet  are  in  no    Pr^lcatlon- 
subject,  as  "the  man"  is  predicated  of  a  subject,  i.  e.  of 

their  original  state,  are  not  predicable  of  substances ;  but  by  the  mental 
act,  we  may  so  connect  an  attribute  with  a  subject,  as  to  render  tin- 
former  predicable  of  the  latter,  as  a  difference,  property,  or  accident. 
When  a  predicate  is  thus  formed  from  an  attribute,  it  is  called  connota- 
tive,  or,  as  Whately  justly  remarks,  "  attributive,"  and  signifies  primarily, 
the  attribute,  and  secondarily,  the  subject  of  inhesion.  Original  uni- 
versal or  attributes,  as  "man,"  "whiteness,"  are  called  "absolute;" 
but  terms  may  be  made  to  cross,  so  that  by  an  act  of  mind,  that  which 
signifies  substance  may  be  conceived  as  an  attribute,  and  as  no  longer 
predicable  of  the  individuals  ;  in  this  sense  they  are  called  "  abstract,"  as 
"  humanitas"  from  "  homo  ;  "  but  when  they  are  primarily  or  secondarily 
predicable  of  individuals,  they  become  "concrete,"  e.  g.  "man"  is  con- 
crete and  absolute;  "  white,"  concrete  and  connotative ;  "whiteness," 
abstract  and  absolute  ;  it  must  be  remembered  only,  that  no  abstract  term 
is  connotative.  Vid.  Occam,  Log.  p.  i.  ch.  5,  10.  Simplicius  enumerates 
eleven  modes  of  predication,  arising  from  the  relations  of  genus  and  spe- 
cies. Aristotle,  in  the  Physics,  divides  substance  in  eight  modes,  omit- 
ting "  time"— considering  subject  as  both  composite  and  individual. 
The  division  into  universals  and  particulars  was  probably  taken  from  the 
categorical  scheme  of  Pythagoras. 

We  annex  a  scheme  of  the  relation  of  subject  to  predicate,  in  respect 
of  consistency  and  inhesion. 


Contrary  to  or  inconsistent  with 


Substance 

\  4> 

/ 

Accment 

u 
tu 

r/ 

.0 

3 
m 

V 

X 

V 

3 
CO 

■*-> 

= 

jF 

.s» 

E- 

■^  £ 

>.£ 

3  •-> 

/ 

\ 

0  .0 
—  3 

O 

/ 

X  *n 

ta 

■a 

0J 

&/, 

X    <*  • 
X  'f 

0 
•a 

0 

.&  /  •  0* 

\% 

— 

'■3 

S-i 

*-> 
a 

■A 

Universal 

\/ 

Particulv 

Sub-contrary  in 

inconsistent  with 

U 

2 

4  Aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  in. 

"  some  certain  man,"  yet  is  in  no  subject.  Others,  again, 
are  in  a  subject,  yet  are  not  predicated  of  any  subject,  (I 
mean  by  a  thing  being  in  a  subject,  that  which  is  in  any 
thing  not  as  a  part,  but  which  cannot  subsist  without  that 
in  which  it  is,)  as  "a  certain  grammatical  art"  is  in  a  sub- 
ject, "  the  soul,"  but  is  not  predicated  of  any ;  and  "  this 
white  thing"  is  in  a  subject,  "the  body,"  (for  all  "colour"  is 
in  "  body,")  but  is  predicated  of  no  subject.  But  some 
things  are  both  predicated  of  and  are  in  a  subject,  as  "  sci- 
ence" is  in  a  subject — "the  soul,"  but  is  predicated  of  a 
subject,  namely,  "grammar."  Lastly,  some  are  neither  in, 
nor  are  predicated  of,  any  subject,  as  "a  certain  man"  and 
"  a  certain  horse,"  for  nothing  of  this  sort  is  either  in,  or 
3.  individuals  predicated  of,  a  certain  subject.  In  short,  indi- 
not  predicated  viduals,  and  whatever  is  one  in  number,  are  pre- 
a  su  jec .  Seated  0f  no  subject,  but  nothing  prevents  some 
of  them  from  being  in  a  subject,  for  "  a  certain  grammatical 
art"  is  amongst  those  things  which  are  in  a  subject,  but  is 
not  predicated  of  any  subject. 


Chap.  III. —  Of  the  connexion  between  Predicate  and  Subject. 


1.  statements  When  one  thing  is  predicated  of  another,  as  of 
!£s"metnt  in  a  subject,  whatever  things  are  said  of  the  predi- 
cate, may  be  also  said  of  the  subject,1  as  "  the 
man"  is  predicated  of  "some  certain  man,"  but  "the  animal" 
is  predicated  of  "the  man,"  wherefore  "the  animal"  will  be 
predicated  of  "some  certain  man,"  since  "the  certain  man"  is 
2  Difference  of  Dotn  "man"  and  "animal."  The  differences  of 
distinct  genera   different  genera,  and  of  things  not  arranged  under 

1  Genera,  species,  and  differences,  differ  according  to  their  predica- 
ments, hence  in  each  predicament,  there  are  genera,  species,  and  differ- 
ences. Those  genera  also,  have  a  mutual  arrangement,  one  of  which  is 
under  the  other,  as  "  flying  "  under  "  animal,"  but  those  are  not  mutually 
arranged,  one  of  which,  is  not  ranked  under  the  other,  as  "animal"  and 
r>  science."  Upon  the  application  of  this  general  rule,  see  Whately  and 
Hill's  Logic,  especially  the  latter,  in  respect  to  summa  and  subaltern 
genera,  and  their  cognates,  pages  56,  57.  Properly  speaking,  there  can 
be  only  one  highest  genus,  namely,  Being ;  though  relatively  a  subaltern 
term,  may  at  any  time,  be  assumed  as  the  summum  genus,  as  "  sub- 
stance,"  "  auimal;  '  etc. 


CHAP.  IT.]  THE    CATEGORIES.  5 

each  other,  are  diverse  also  in  species,1  as  of  "  ani-   induces  differ 
mal"  and  "science."    For  the  differences  of  " ani-   unfcrthem.'* 
raal"  are  "quadruped,"  "biped,"  "winged,"  "aquatic,"  but 
none  of  these,  forms  the  difference  of  "science,"  since  "sci- 
ence," does  not  differ  from  "  science,"  in  being   3  Not  so  as 
"  biped."     But  as  to  subaltern  genera,  there  is   subaltern  ge- 
nothing  to  prevent  the  differences  being  the  same, 
as  the  superior  are  predicated  of  the  genera  under  them  ;  so 
that  as  many  differences  as  there  are  of  the  predicate,  so  many 
will  there  also  be  of  the  subject. 

Chap.  IV. — Enumeration  of  the  Categories. 

Of  things  incomplex  enunciated,  each  signifies   j  ofincom- 
either  Substance,  or  Quantity,  or  Quality,  or  Re-   pie*  "re- 
lation, or  Where,  or  When,  or  Position,  or  Pos- 
session, or  Action,  or  Passion.2     But  Substance  is,  (to  speak 
generally,)    as    "man,"    "horse;"    Quantity,   as    "two"   or 
"three  cubits  ;"  Quality,  as  "white,"  a  "grammatical  thing  ;" 
Relation,  as  "  a  double,"  "  a  half,"  "  greater  ; "  Where,  as  "  in 
the  Forum,"  "in  the  Lyceum  ;"  When,  as  "yesterday,"  "last 
year;"   Position,  as  "he  reclines,"  "he  sits;"  Possession,  as 
"  he  is  shod,"  "  he  is  armed ; "   Action,  as  "  he  cuts,"  "  he 
burns  ; "  Passion,  as  "  he  is  cut,"  "  he  is  burnt."   2.  categories 
Now  each  of  the  above,  considered  by  itself,  is   by  themselves, 

'  •>  .'  neither  affirm- 

predicated   neither   affirmatively  nor  negatively,   ative  nor  nega- 
but  from  the  connexion  of  these  with  each  other,   tive- 
affirmation  or  negation  arises.    For  every  affirmation  or  nega- 
tion appears  to  be  either  true  or  false,  but  of  things  enun- 

1  Difference  joined  to  genus  constitutes  species — it  is  called  specific 
difference,  when  it  constitutes  the  lowest  species,  as  of  individuals.  Cf. 
Crakanthorpe  Logica,  lib.  ii.  The  common  definitions  of  the  heads  of 
the  predicables,  are  those  of  Porphyry,  adopted  by  subsequent  logicians. 
Vide  Porph.  Isagoge. 

2  The  principle  of  distinction  above  is  shown  to  be  grammatical,  by 
Trendelenburg,  Elementa,  section  3rd.  The  six  last  may  be  reduced  to 
Relation,  see  Hamilton  on  Reid,  p.  688.  The  categories  are  enu- 
merated and  exemplified  in  the  following  verses,  for  the  student's  recol- 
lection. 

Summa  decern  :  Substantia,  Quantum,  Quale,  Relatio, 
Actio,  Passio.     Ubi,  Quando,  Situs,  Habitus. 
Presbyter  exilis,  specie  pater,  orat  et  ardet. 
In  campo,  semper  rectus,  et  in  tunica. 


6  Aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  v. 

ciated  without  any  connexion,  none  is  either  true  or  false,  as 
"man,"  "white,"  "runs,"  "conquers." 


Chap.  V. — Of  Substance} 

1.  Primary  sub-   Substance,  in  its  strictest,  first,  and  chief  sense, 
stance  is  net      js  that  which  is  neither  predicated  of  any  subject, 

ther  in,  nor  is  .     .  l     .  „  J  J     . 

predicated  of,  nor  is  in  any ;  as  "  a  certain  man.  or  "  a  certain 
^Secondary  horse."  But  secondary  substances  are  they,  in 
substances  con-  which  as  species,  those  primarily-named  sub- 
stances are  inherent,  that  is  to  say,  both  these 
and  the  genera  of  these  species  ;2  as  "a  certain  man"  exists 
in  "man,"  as  in  a  species,  but  the  genus  of  this  species  is 
"  animal ; "  these,  therefore,  are  termed  secondary  substances, 

1  On  the  various  modes  in  which  Aristotle  employs  the  term  oixria, 
cf.  Metaphy.  lib.  iv.,  and  Phys.  lib.  iii.  Without  entering  into  the 
dispute  relative  to  the  real  existence  of  genera  and  species,  as  substances 
independent  of  us,  between  the  old  Realists  and  the  modern  Conceptual- 
ists,  it  will  be  sufficient  to  state  that  Aristotle  here  employs  the  term  as 

'  the  summum  genus,  under  which,  by  continued  abstraction  of  differences, 
>  all  things  may  be  comprehended  as  a  common  universal.  Thus  also 
Plato  in  Repub.  lib.  vii.  Whether  called  Entity,  Being,  Substance,  or 
Subsistence,  it  may  be  defined,  "  That  which  subsists  independently  of 
any  other  created  thing,"  and  in  this  view  may  be  affirmatively  predi- 
cated of  every  cognate  term,  though  no  cognate  term  can  be  so  predi- 
cated of  it :  thus  all  bodies,  all  animals,  all  lions,  etc.,  are  substances 
or  things,  according  as  we  adopt  either  of  these  last  as  summum  genus. 
Archytas  places  essence  first ;  Plotinus  and  Nicostratus  doubt  its  generic 
affinity  altogether ;  but  all  regard  the  principle  laid  down,  of  some  one, 
independent,  existence,  or  conception. 

2  But  in  getting  to  this  ultimate  abstraction,  the  first  common  nature 
of  which  the  mind  forms  conception  from  individual  comparison,  is  called 
the  lowest  primary  or  most  specific  species,  and  of  this,  every  cognate  term 
may  be  universally  predicated,  though  itself  canno*  be  predicated  of  any 
cognate  term.  Between  these  extremes,  all  intermediate  notions  (and  their 
verbal  signs)  are  called  subaltern,  each  of  which,  like  the  step  of  a  lad- 
der, is  at  once  superior  to  some  and  inferior  to  others,  and  becomes  a 
genus  in  relation  to  some  lower  species,  and  a  species  to  some  higher 
genera.  The  annexed  "  Arbor  Porphyriana"  is  given  by  Aquinas,  Opusc. 
48.  Tract.  2,  cap.  3.  In  all  the  earlier  specimens,  "animal  rationale" 
is  placed  between  "Animal"  and  "Homo,"  as  the  proximum  genus, 
divided  into  "  mortale"  and  "  immortale,"  in  accordance  with  Porphyry's 
definition  of  man.  We  shall  here  observe  also,  that  a  summum  genus  can 
have  no  constitutive  differences,  which  are  represented  at  the  side,  though 
a  summum  genus  may  have  properties. 


ch'ap.  V  ] 


THE    CATEGORIES. 


as  both  "man"  and  "animal."1    But  it  is  evident    ,  T       A. 

3.  In  predica- 

from  what  has  been  said,  that  or  those  things   tion  the  name 
which  are  predicated  of  a  subject,  both  the  name   ofth^subjeet 
and  the  definition  must  be  predicated  of  the  sub-  must  be  predi- 
ject,  as  "man"  is  predicated  of  "some  certain 
man,"  as  of  a  subject,  and  the  name,  at  least,  is  predicated,  for 
you  will  predicate  "man"  of  "some  certain  man,"  and  the 


Substantia 


,\sV* 


Corporea 


Animatum 


Sensibile 


Rationale 


Incorporea 


Inanimatum 


Insensibile 


Irrationale 


Socrates 


Plato 


»  For  the  method  of  predication,  vide  Huyshe,  Aldrich,  or  Whately. 
Also  compare  the  Topics  iv.  2,  Isagoge  2,  Aquinas  Opusc  48,  cap.  2. 
Genus  and  species  are  said  "  praedicari  in  quid,"  l.  e.  are  expressed  by 
a  substantive ;  Property  and  Accident  "  in  quale,"  or  by  an  adjective. 
This  whole  chapter,  brings  forcibly  to  the  mind,  Butler's  satirical  bur- 
lesoue  of  Hudibrastic  acumen,  in  discovering 

"  Where  entity  and  quiddity, 

The  ghosts  of  defunct  bodies  fly  !  " 

Iludibras,  Part  i.  Can.  1. 
Though  very  necessary,  the  initiative  processes  of  Logic,  indeed  present 

"  A  kind  of  Babylonish  dialect, 

Which  learned  pedants  much  affect" 


8  Aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  v. 

definition  of  man  will  be  predicated  of  "  some  certain  man," 
for  "a  certain  man"  is  both  "man"  and  "animal;"  where- 

fore  both  the  name  and  the  definition  will  be  pre- 
happens  in  the  dicated  of  a  subject.  But  of  things  which  are  in 
inneskinT113'      a  SUDJect>  for  the  most  part,  neither  the  name  nor 

the  definition  is  predicated  of  the  subject,  yet  with 
some,  there  is  nothing  to  prevent  the  name  from  being  some- 
times predicated  of  the  subject,  though  the  definition  cannot 
be  so;  as  "whiteness"  being  in  a  body,  as  in  a  subject,  is 
predicated  of  the  subject,  (for  the  body  is  termed  "white,") 
but  the  definition  of  "whiteness"  can  never  be  predicated  of 
body.  All  other  things,  however,  are  either  predicated  of 
primary  substances,  as  of  subjects,  or  are  inherent  in  them 
as  in  subjects ; l  this,  indeed,  is  evident,  from  several  obvi- 
ous instances,  thus  "  animal "  is  predicated  of  "  man,"  and 
therefore  is  also  predicated  of  some  "  certain  man,"  for  if  it 

5.  Theuni-  were  predicated  of  no  "man"  particularly,  nei- 
versai  involves   ther  could  it  be  of  "  man "  universally.     Again, 

"colour"  is  in  "body,"  therefore  also  is  it  in 
"some  certain  body,"  for  if  it  were  not  in  "some  one"  of 
bodies  singularly,  it  could  not  be  in  "body"  universally; 
so  that  all  other  things  are  either  predicated  of  primary  sub- 
stances as  of  subjects,  or  are  inherent  in  them  as  in  subjects ; 
if  therefore  the  primal  substances  do  not  exist,  it  is  impossible 
that  any  one  of  the  rest  should  exist. ' 

6.  species  more  But  °f  secondary  substances,  species  is  more 
a  substance        substance  than  genus  ; 2  for  it  is  nearer  to  the 

primary  substance,  and  if  any  one  explain  what 
the  primary  substance  is,  he  will  explain  it  more  clearly  and 
appropriately  by  giving  the  species,  rather  than  the  genus ; 
as  a  person  defining  "  a  certain  man "  would  do  so  more 
clearly,  by  giving  "  man  "  than  "  animal,"  for  the  former  is 
more  the  peculiarity  of  "  a  certain  man,"  but  the  latter  is 
more  common.  In  like  manner,  whoever  explains  what  "a 
certain  tree  "  is,  will  define  it  in  a  more  known  and  appropri- 

7.  Primary  sub-  ate  manner,  by  introducing  "tree"  than  "plant." 
subjects^au6  Besides  the  primary  substances,  because  of  their 
predicates;        subjection  to  all  other  things,  and  these  last  being 

1  Plato,  in  the  Philebus,  observes,  that  a  philosopher  ought  not  to  de- 
scend, below  wholes,  and  common  natures. 

s  Vidt  supra,  note ;  also  Metaph.  lib.  iv.  and  vi. 


CHAP.  V.]  THE    CATEGORIES.  9 

either  predicated  of  them,  or  being  in  them,  are  for   hence  tb<?!<- 
this  reason,  especially,  termed  substances.  Yet  the   name* 
same  relation  as  the  primary  substances  bear  to  all  other  things, 
does  species  bear  to  genus,  for  species  is  subjected  to  genus 
since  genera  are  predicated  of  species,  but  species   8.  Genus  a  pre 
are  not  reciprocally  predicated  of  genera,  whence   d.icat e  of  sPe_ 
the  species  is  rather  substance  than  the  genus.  „     vice  vend. 
Of  species  themselves,  however,  as  many  as  are   9.  infimffi 
not  genera,  are  not  more  substance,  one  than  an-   species  are 
other,  for  he  will  not  give  a  more  appropriate   not  being 'sub- 
definition   of  "  a  certain  man,"  who  introduces   stance- 
"  man,"  than  he  who  introduces  "  horse,"  into  the  definition  of 
"a  certain  horse:"    in  like  manner  of  primary  substances, 
one  is  not  more  substance  than  another,  for  "  a  certain  man  " 
is  not  more  substance  than  a  "  certain  ox."     With  reason 
therefore,  after  the  first  substances,  of  the  rest, 
species  and  genera  alone  are  termed  secondary   genera  alone" 
substances,  since  they  alone  declare  the  primary  are  secondary 

*       Sli list  in  pp'n 

substances  of  the  predicates  ;  thus,  if  any  one  were 
to  define  what  "a  certain  man"  is,  he  would,  by  giving  the 
species  or  the  genus,  define  it  appropriately,  and  will  do  30 
more   clearly  by  introducing   "man"  than  "animal;"   but 
whatever  else  he  may  introduce,  he  will  be  introducing,  in 
a  manner,  foreign  to  the  purpose,  as  if  he  were  to  introduce 
"  white,"  or  "  runs,"  or  any  thing  else  of  the  kind,  so  that 
with  propriety  of  the   others,  these  alone  are  termed  sub- 
stances.    Moreover,  the  primary  substances,  be- 
cause they  are  subject  to  all  the  rest,  and  all  the   ^'atfo^be-5  °f 
others  are  predicated  of,  or  exist  in,  these,  are  most   tween  cognate 
properly  termed  substances,  but  the  same  relation   species.3" 
which  the  primary  substances  bear  to  all  other 
things,  do  the  species  and  genera  of  the  first  substances  bear  to 
all  the  rest,  since  of  these,  are  all  the  rest  predicated,  for  you 
will  say  that  "  a  certain  man  "  is  "  a  grammarian,''  and  therefore 
you  will  call  both  "  man"  and  "  animal"  "  a  grammarian,"  and 
in  like  manner  of  the  rest.1 

1  Archytas  adopts  a  different  division  of  substance,  into  matter,  form, 
and  a  composite  of  the  two,  and  this  division  Aristotle  shows  in  his 
Physics,  and  Metaphysics,  and  Physical  Auscultation  he  knew,  but  doflfl 
not  employ  it  in  this  treatise,  as  not  adapted  for  its  subject  matter, 
namely,  logical  discussion.  Cf.  Physica  Ausc.  lib.  iii.,  and  Metaph.  lib. 
ri.  and  xi. 


10  akistotle's  organon.  [chap.  V 


i?  No  sub-  It  ^s  common  however  to  every  substance,  not  to 

stance  m  a  sub-  be  in  a  subject,1  for  neither  is  the  primal  substance  in 
a  subject,  nor  is  it  predicated  of  any  ;  but  of  the  se- 
condary substances,  that  none  of  them  is  in  a  subject,  is  evident 
from  this;  "man"  is  predicated  of  "some  certain"  subject 
"  man,"  but  is  not  in  a  subject,  for  "  man  "  is  not  in  "  a  cer- 
tain man."  So  also  "  animal "  is  predicated  of  "  some  certain  " 
13  of  inhe-  subject  "man,"*but  "  animal"  is  not  in  "a  certain 
sives  the  name  man."  Moreover  of  those  which  are,  in  the  sub- 
catedof  thee  '"  ject,  nothing  prevents  the  name  from  being  some- 
subject;,  but  not   tjmes  predicated  of  the  subject,  but  that  the  defi- 

the  definition.         .   .        r  •>        >    . 

nition  should  be  predicated  ot  it,  is  impossible. 
Of  secondary  substances  however  the  definition  and  the  name 
are  both  predicated  of  the  subject,  for  you  will  predicate  the 

definition  of  "  a  man"  concerning;  "  a  certain  man," 


o 


may  b^  predi-   and  likewise  the  definition  of  "  animal,"  so  that 
cated  of  second-   substance,  may  not  be  amongst  the  number,  of  those 

ary  substances.  .       J  .  .  ° 

things  which  are  in  a  subject. 
is.  Difference         This  however  is  not  the  peculiarity  of  sub- 
does  not  exist   stance,  but  difference  also  is  of  the  number  of 

m  subject.  '  .  . 

those  things  not  in  a  subject;2  lor  "pedestrian  ' 
and  "  biped "  are  indeed  predicated  of  "  a  man "  as  of  a 
subject,  but  are  not  in  a  subject,  for  neither  "  biped "  nor 
"  pedestrian "  is  in  "  man,"  The  definition  also  of  differ- 
ence is  predicated  of  that,  concerning  which,  difference  is  pre- 
dicated, so  that  if  "  pedestrian  "  be  predicated  of  "man,"  the 
definition  also  of  "  pedestrian  "  will  be  predicated  of  man,  for 

"  man"  is  "  pedestrian."  Nor  let  the  parts  of  sub- 
substances'  are  stances,  being  in  wholes  as  in  subjects,  perplex  us, 
also  sub-  so  that  we  should  at  any  time  be  compelled  to  say, 

that  they  are  not  substances ;  for  in  this  manner, 

1  Simplicius  observes  that  Aristotle  discusses  the  things  which  sub- 
stance has  in  common  with  the  other  predicaments  ;  Iamblichus,  what  is 
common  to  it,  and  also  its  property  and  difference.  Some  may  doubt 
how  essence,  will  not  be  in  a  subject,  as  ideas  according  to  Plato  are  in 
intellect,  yet  these  are  neither  as  in  a  subject,  but  are  as  essence  in  an- 
other essence:  Aristotle  discusses  this  in  the  12th  book  of  the  Metaphysics. 

2  Generic  difference,  it  must  be  remembered,  constitutes  subaltern  spe- 
cies— specific  difference,  forms  the  lowest  species — the  former  difference 
is  predicated  of  things  different  in  species,  the  latter  of  things  differing  in 
number.  In  the  scholastic  theory,  the  properties  of  the  summum  genus 
were  regarded  as  flowing  from  the  simple  substance,  those  of  all  subor- 
dinate classes,  from  the  differentia.    See  Hill's  Logic  on  the  Predicables 


CHAP.  V.]  THE    CATEGORIES.  )  1 

things  would  not  be  said  to  be  in   a  subject,  which  are   in 
any  as  parts.  It  happens  indeed  both  to  substances 
and  to  differences  alike,  that  all  things  should  be   ^S™ 
predicated  of  them  univocally,  for  all  the  cate-    substance  nre- 

r      .        ,.  ,,  t      .     i      -,1  •  dicated   univo- 

gones  from  them  are  predicated  either  in  respect   caUy. 
of  individuals  or  of  species,  since  from  the  primary 
substance  there  is  no  category,  for  it  is  predicated  in  respect 
of  no  subject.     But  of  secondary  substances,  species  indeed 
is  predicated  in  respect  of  the  individual,  but  genus  in  respect 
to  species  and  to  individuals,  so  also  differences  are  predicated 
as  to  species  and  as  to  individuals.     Again,  the 
primary  substances  take  the  definition  of  species 
and  of  genera,  and  the  species  the  definition  of  the  genus,  for 
as  many  things  as  are  said  of  the  predicate,  so  many  also  will 
be  said  of  the  subject,  likewise  both  the  species  and  the  indi- 
viduals accept  the  definition  of  the  differences :  those  things 
at  least  were  univocal,  of  which  the  name  is  common  and  the 
definition  the  same,  so  that  all  which  arise  from  substances 
and  differences  are  predicated  univocally. 

Nevertheless  every  substance  appears  to  signify   19  A11  sub. 
this  particular  thing :  •  as  regards  then  the  pri-   stance  signifies 

1  .  °  .  D..         ,,  \      ,     some  one  thing. 

mary  substances,  it  is  unquestionably  true  that 
they  signify  a  particular  thing,  for  what  is  signified  is  indi- 
vidual, and  one  in  number,  but  as  regards  the  secondary  sub- 
stances, it  appears  in  like  manner  that  they  signify  this  par- 
ticular thing,  by  the  figure  of  appellation,  when  any  one  says 
"  man  "  or  "  animal,"  yet  it  is  not  truly  so,  but  20  SecoI,dary 
rather  they  signify  a  certain  quality,  for  the  sub-   substances  sig- 

1  It  was  the  opinion  of  Kant,  as  well  as  of  Reid  and  Stewart,  that  in 
mind,  as  in  body,  substance  and  unity  are  not  presented  but  represented, 
but  what  the  thine/  itself  is,  which  is  the  subject  and  owner  of  the  several 
qualities,  yet  not  identical  with  any  one  of  them,  can  only  be  conceived, 
in  as  far  as  we  can  attain  to  any  single  conception  of  the  to  ov — through 
its  many  modifications,  which  attainment  is  itself  questionable.  \  ide 
some  admirable  remarks  in  Mansel's  Prolego.  Log.  '277.  Generally  it 
suffices  to  retain  the  quaint  form  of  the  schools  noticed  above  upon  pre- 
dication of  genus  and  species.  Vide  Aldrich's  Logic.  Genus  is  a  whole 
logically,  but  species  metaphysically,  or,  as  they  may  be  better  expressed, 
the  first  is  Totum  Universale,  the  second  Totuui  Essentiale.  Cf.  Cra- 
kanthorpe  Logica,  lib.  ii.  cap.  5.  Since  writing  the  above,  the  striking 
illustration  occurs  to  me,  used  by  Lord  Shaftesbury,  of  "  the  person  left 
within,  who  has  power  to  dispute  the  appearances,  and  redress,  the  ima- 
gination." Shaftesbury's  Charac.  vol.  i.  p.  325.  The  passage  has  mora 
sense  than,  yet  as  much  sound  as,  any  of  his  Lordship's  writing. 


12  Aristotle's  organ  on.  [chap.  v. 

r.ify  a  certain  ject  is  not  one,  as  the  primary  substance,  but  "  man  '' 
"quale.  an(j  «  anmiai "  are  predicated  in  respect  of  many. 

Neither  do  they  signify  simply  a  certain  quality,  as  "  white," 
for  "  white "  signifies  nothing  else  but  a  thing  of  a  certain 
quality,  but  the  species  and  the  genus  determine  the  quality, 
about  the  substance,  for  they  signify  what  quality  a  certain 
substance  possesses :  still  a  wider  limit  is  made  by  genus 
than  by  species,  for  whoever  speaks  of  "  animal,"  comprehends 
more  than  he  who  speaks  of  "  man." 

v  It  belongs  also  to  substances  that  there  is  no 
su'bstlrlce  ad-  contrary  to  them,  *  since  what  can  be  contrary  to  the 
mits  no  con-  primary  substance,  as  to  a  certain  "  man,"  or  to  a 
certain  "  animal,"  for  there  is  nothing  contrary 
either  at  least  to  "  man  "  or  to  "  animal  ?  "  Now  this  is  not  the 
peculiarity  of  substance,  but  of  many  other  things,  as  for  in- 
stance of  quantity  ;  for  there  is  no  contrary  to  "two" 
ttewes™ in"  cubits  nor  to  "  three  "  cubits,  nor  to  "  ten,"  nor  to  any 
thing  of  the  kind,  unless  some  one  should  say  that 
"  much"  is  contrary  to  "  little,"  or  "  the  great"  to  "  the  small ; " 
but  of  definite  quantities,  none  is  contrary  to  the  other.  Sub- 
stance, also,  appears  not  to  receive  greater  or  less  ; 2 
greaternorie'ss!  I  mean,  not  that  one  substance  is  not,  more  or  less, 
substance,  than  another,  for  it  has  been  already 
said  that  it  is,  but  that  every  substance  is  not  said  to  be 
more  or  less,  that  very  thing,  that  it  is ;  as  if  the  same  sub- 
stance be  "  man  "  he  will  not  be  more  or  less  "  man  ;"  neither 
himself  than  himself,  nor  another  "  man  "  than  another,  for 
one  "  man  "  is  not  more  "  man  "  than  another,  as  one  "  white 
thing"  is  more  and  less  "white"  than  another,  and  one 
"  beautiful"  thing  more  and  less  "  beautiful"  than  another,  and 
"the  same  thing"  more  or  less  than  "itself;"  so  a  body  being 
"  white,"  is  said  to  be  more  "  white  "  now,  than  it  was  before, 
and  if  "  warm  "  is  said  to  be  more  or  less  "  warm."  Substance 
at  least  is  not  termed  more  or  less  substance,  since  "  man  " 
is  not  said  to  be  more  "man"  now,  than  before,  nor  any 

1  This,  says  Simplicius,  is  doubted  by  some,  and  indeed  in  his  Physics, 
lib.  i.,  Aristotle  apparently  contradicts  his  own  statement  above  by  in- 
stancing Form  as  the  contrary  to  Privation,  both  being  substantial ;  but 
Form  is  but  partly,  substance,  and  partly,  habit,  and  only  in  so  much  as  it 
is  the  latter,  is  it  contrary  to  Privation,  not  "  quoad  substantiam." 

2  This  is  true,  discrete  quantities  being  unchangeable,  and  definite  ia 
quantity. 


CIIA.P.   V.]  THE    CATEGORIES.  13 

one  of  such  other  things  as  are  substances :  hence  substance 
is  not  capable  of  receiving  the  greater  and  the  less. 

It  appears  however,  to  be  especially  the  pecu-   24.  individu- 
liarity  of  substance,  that  being  one  and  the  same   ceweVontr"^- 
in  number,  it  can  receive  contraries,  which  no  one   ries.> in  wnicn 
can  affirm  of  the  rest  which  are  not  substances,   those  which  we 
as  that  being  one  in  number,  they  are  capable  of  not  substanc*s- 
contraries.1     Thus  "  colour,"  which  is  one  and  the  same  in 
number,  is  not  "  white  "  and  "  black,"  neither  the  same  action, 
also  one  in  number,  both  bad  and  good  ;  in  like  manner  of  other 
things  as  many  as  are  not  substances.     But  substance  being 
one,  and  the  same  in  number,  can  receive  contraries,  as  "  a 
certain  man  "  being  one  and  the  same,  is  at  one  time,  white, 
and  at  another,  black,  and  warm  and  cold,  and  bad  and  good. 
In  respect  of  none  of  the  rest  does  such  a  thing  appear,  ex- 
cept some  one  should  object,  by  saying,  that  a  sentence  and 
opinion  are  capable  of  receiving  contraries,  for  the  same  sen- 
tence appears  to  be  true  and  false ;  thus  if  the  statement  be 
true  that  "  some  one  sits,"  when  he  stands  up,  this 
very  same  statement  will  be  false.     And  in  a  si-   objection  by  a 
milar  manner  in   the  matter  of  opinion,   for  if  j^g nce  t0  the 
any  one  should  truly  opine  that  a  certain  person 
sits,  when  he  rises  up  he  will  opine  falsely,  if  he  still  holds 
the  same  opinion  about  him.     Still,  if  any  one,  should  even 
admit  this,  yet  there  is  a  difference  in  the  mode.   2e  x  h 
For  some  things  in  substances,  being  themselves   in  substances 
changed,  are  capable  of  contraries,  since  cold,  be-   change'tTcapa- 
ing  made   so,  from  hot,  has  changed,   for  it  is   ble  ot  contra- 
changed  in  quality,  and  black  from  white,  and 
good  from  bad :   in  like  manner  as  to  other  things,  each  one 
of  them  receiving  change  is  capable  of  contraries.     The  sen- 
tence indeed  and  the  opinion   remain  themselves  altogether 
immovable,  but  the  thing  being  moved,  a   contrary  is  pro- 
duced about  them;  the  sentence  indeed  remains  the  same, 
that  "  some  one  sits,"  but  the  thing  being  moved,  it  becomes 
at  one  time,  true,  and  at  another,  false.    Likewise  as  to  opinion, 

1  He  does  not  mean  that  contraries  exist  in  substance  at  one  and  the 
same  time,  as  may  be  perceived  from  the  examples  he  adduces.  Archy- 
tas,  according  to  Simplicius,  admits  the  capability  of  contraries  to  be  the 
peculiarity  of  substance  ;  "  thus  vigilance  is  contrary  to  sleep,  slowness 
to  swiftness,  disease  to  health,  ot'all  which,  one  and  the  same  man,  is  capa- 
ble."   Simp,  in  Anst.  Cat.    Compare  also  Wai'.z,  Organ,  p.  2'Jl,  Comment. 


14  aristotle's  organon.  [ciiap.  vi. 

so  that  in  this  way,  it  will  be  the  peculiarity  of  substance,  to 
receive  contraries  according  to  the  change  in  itself,  but  if  any 
one  admitted  this,  that  a  sentence  and  opinion  can  receive 
contraries,  this  would  not  be  true.  For  the  sen- 
5J"„.S5U^n     tence  and  the  opinion  are  not  said  to  be  capable 

QT.  paSSlOll  111  -*■  J- 

the  example  as   of  contraries  in  that  they  have  received  any  thing, 
opinion  but,  in  that  about  something  else,  a  passive  qua- 

lity has  been  produced,  for  in  that  a  thing  is,  or 
is  not,  in  this,  is  the  sentence  said  to  be  true,  or  false,  not  in 
that  itself,  is  capable  of  contraries.1  In  short,  neither  is  a  sen- 
tence nor  an  opinion  moved  by  any  thing,  whence  they  can- 
not be  capable  of  contraries,  no  passive  quality  being  in  them  ; 
substance  at  least,  from  the  fact  of  itself  receiving  contraries, 
is  said  in  this  to  be  capable  of  contraries,  for  it  receives  dis- 
ease and  health,  whiteness  and  blackness,  and  so  long  as  it 
receives  each  of  these,  it  is  said  to  be  capable  of  receiving 
contraries.  Wherefore  it  will  be  the  peculiarity  of  substance, 
that  being  the  same,  and  one  in  number,  according  to  change 
in  itself,  it  is  capable  of  receiving  contraries  ;  and  concerning 
substance  this  may  suffice.2 

Chap.  VI.— Of  Quantity? 

1.  Quantity       Of  Quantity,  one  kind  is  discrete,  and  another 
two-fold, dis-      continuous;4   the  one  consists  of  parts,   holding 

1  Simplicius  alleges  that  certain  Peripatetics  asserted  that  matter  itself 
was  susceptible  of  TrdBoQ.  It  must  be  remembered  however  that  Aris- 
totle's definition  of  irdOt]  (Rhet.  lib.  i.)  is,  that  they  are  certain  things 
added  to  substance,  beyond  its  own  nature.  Vide  Scholia  ad  Categorias, 
ed.  Waitz,  p.  32.     Leip.  1844. 

2  The  union  between  ovaia  and  v\r]  is  laid  down  in  the  treatise  de 
Anima,  lib.  ii.  1 ,  sec.  2  :  the  latter  term  was  used  by  the  schoolmen  to 
signify  the  subject  matter  upon  which  any  art  was  employed,  in  which 
sense,  it  was  tantamount  to  primal  substance. 

3  Some  say  that  quantity,  is  considered  in  juxta-position  with  substance, 
because  it  subsists  together  with  it,  for  after  substance  is  admitted,  it  is 
necessary  to  inquire  whether  it  is  one  or  many ;  others,  because  among 
other  motions,  that  which  is  according  to  quantity,  viz.  increase  and 
diminution,  is  nearer  to  the  notion  of  substance,  viz.  generation  and  cor- 
ruption, than  "  alliation "  is,  which  is  a  motion  according  to  quality. 
Taylor.  Vide  ch.  8,  and  Sulpicius,  concerning  the  nature  of  this  last.  See 
also,  Arist.  Phys.  lib.  iii.  et  v.,  also  cf.  Cat.  ch.  14. 

4  Conf.  Metaphy.  lib.  iv.  cap.  13,  Yloabv  Xkytrat  to  Siaiperbv  etQ 
fvviraQXovra,  k.  t.  X.  The  reader  will  do  well  (o  compare  the  above 
chapter,  throughout,  with  that  quoted  from  the  Metaphysics,  where 
these  terms  are  all  used  equivocally. 


CI1A.P.  VI.]  THE    CATEGORIES.  15 

position  with  respect  to  each  other,  but  the  other  crete  and  eonu- 
of  parts,  which  have  not  that  position.  Dis-  occ^yingreia* 
crete  quantity  is,  as  number  and  sentence,  but   the  position, 

i.  j         ?  and  tiic  con- 

continuous,    as    line,    superficies,    body,    besides   trary. 
place  and  time.     For,  of  the  parts  of  number,   |*is^et™plea 
there  is  no  common  term,  by  which  its  parts  con-    I.  Number. 
join,  as  if  five  be  a  part  of  ten,  five  and  five,  conjoin  at  no 
common  boundary,  but  are  separated.    Three,  and  seven,  also 
conjoin  at  no  common  boundary,  nor  can  you  at  all  take  a 
common  limit  of  parts,  in  number,  but  they  are  always  separ- 
ated, whence  number  is  of  those  things  which 

0  „  2.  uratio. 

are  discrete.  In  like  manner  a  sentence,  ior 
that  a  sentence  is  quantity  is  evident,  since  it  is  measured 
by  a  short  and  long  syllable  ; l  but  I  mean  a  sentence  produced 
by  the  voice,  as  its  parts  concur  at  no  common  limit,  for  there 
is  no  common  limit,  at  which  the  syllables  concur,  but  each  is 
distinct  by  itself.  A  line,  on  the  contrary,  is  3  Examples 
continuous,  for  you  may  take  a  common  term,  at   continuous. 

....  i  ■    ,  jj?1-A  line. 

which  its  parts  meet,  namely,  a  point,  and  ot  a 
superficies,  a  line,  for  the  parts  of  a  superficies  coalesce  in  a 
certain  common  term.     So  also  you  can  take  a  common  term 
in  respect  of  body,  namely,  a  line,  or  a  superficies,  2  Asuperficies 
by  which  the  parts  of  body  are  joined.     Of  the 
same  sort  are  time  and  place,  for  the  present  time  is  joined 
both  to  the  past  and  to  the  future.     Again,  place   3.  Time  and 
is  of  the  number  of  continuous  things,  for  the   Place- 
parts  of  a  body  occupy  a  certain  place,  which  parts  join  at  a 
certain  common  boundary,  wherefore  also  the  parts  of  place, 
which  each  part  of  the  body  occupies,  join  at  the  same  bound- 
ary as  the  parts  of  the  body,  so  that  place  will  also  be  con- 
tinuous, since  its  parts  join  at  one  common  boundary. 

Moreover,  some  things  consist  of  parts,  having   4  Relative 
position  with  respect  to  each  other,  but  others  of  sition  of  some 
parts  not  having  such  position  ;2  thus  the  parts  of  ^as  t0  the 
a  line  have  relative  position,  for  each  of  them  lies 

1  Aristotle  means  by  Xoyoc,  a  sentence  subsisting  in  voice,  not  in  intel- 
lect. Sulpic.  He  adds  also,  that  Archytas,  Athenodorus,  and  Ptolemy 
condemn  the  division  of  quantity  into  two  kinds,  and  prefer  that  ot  num- 
ber, magnitude,  and  momentum,  but  the  reply  is,  that  the  last  is  a  quality, 
the  same  as  density. 

2  Plotinus,  in  his  first  book  on  the  Genera  of  Being,  says,  if  the  con- 
tinued, is  quantity,  discrete,  cannot  be ;  but  he  questions  it  as  existing  in 


16  Aristotle's  okganon.  [chap.  vi. 

some  where,  and  you  can  distinguish,  and  set  out,  where  each 
lies,  in  a  superficies,  and  to  which  part  of  the  rest,  it  is  joined., 
83  also  the  pans  of  a  superficies,  have  a  certain  position,  for 
it  may  be  in  like  manner  pointed  out  where  each  lies,  and 
what  have  relation  to  each  other,  and  the  parts  of  a  solid,  and 
of  a  place,  in  like  manner.     On  the  contrary,  in 

5.   Parts  have  .      0  ,  ....  mip 

no  relation  in     respect  or  number,  it  is  impossible  tor  any  one  to 
respect  of  num-  show  that  its  parts  have  any  relative  position,  or 

ber  or  time.  *.  J  r  .  ' 

that  they  are  situated  any  where,  or  which  ot  t he- 
parts  are  joined  to  each  other.  Nor  as  regards  parts  of  time, 
for  not  one  of  the  parts  of  time  endures,  but  that  which 
does  not  endure,  how  can  it  have  any  position  ?  you  would 
rather  say,  that  they  have  a  certain  order,  inasmuch  as  one 
part  of  time  is  former,  but  another  latter.  In  the  same  man- 
ner is  it  with  number,  because  one,  is  reckoned  before  two, 
and  two,  before  three,  and  so  it  may  have  a  certain  order,  but 

you  can,  by  no  means,  assume,  that  it  has  position. 

A  speech  likewise,  for  none  of  its  parts  en- 
dures, but  it  has  been  spoken,  and  it  is  no  longer  possible  to 
bring  back  what  is  spoken,  so  that  there  can  be  no  position 
of  its  parts,  since  not  one  endures :  some  things  therefore 
consist  of  parts  having  position,  but  others  of  those  which 

have  not  position.  What  we  have  enumerated 
named  aretfie  are  alone  properly  termed  quantities  ;  all  the  rest 
only  proper        being  so  denominated  by  accident,   for  looking 

quanta— all  ,,0  n        ,  i  •  •   •  ,  •     ° 

others  reduci-     to  these,  we  call  other  things  quantities,  as  white- 

ExampiesT  _    ness  *s  sa*^  *°  ^e  mucn?  because  the  superficies  is 
great,  and  an  action  long,  because  of  its  time  be- 
insr  lone,  and  motion  also,  is  termed,  much.     Yet  each  of 


*o 


these  is  not  called  a  quantity  by  itself,  for  if  a  man  should 
explain  the  quantity  of  an  action,  he  will  define  it  by  time, 
describing  it  as  yearly,  or  something  of  the  sort ;  and  if  he 
were  to  explain  the  quantity  of  whiteness,  he  will  define  it  by 
the  superficies,  for  as  the  quantity  of  the  superficies,  so  he 
would  say  is  the  quantity  of  the  whiteness  ;  whence  the  par- 
ticulars we  have  mentioned  are  alone  properly  of  themselves 
termed  quantities,  none  of  the  rest  being  so  of  itself,  but  ac- 

the  intellect,  and  confounds  the  distinction  between  order,  in  discrete, 
and  position,  in  continued  quantities.  The  point  is  touched  upon  also  in 
lib.  vi.  of  the  Physics.  Compare  also  ch.  12,  on  Priority,  in  the  Cate- 
gories, as  to  the  relation  in  respect  of  number  and  time. 


CHAP.  VI.]  THE   CATEGORIES  17 

cording  to  accident.     Again,  nothing  is  contrary   8  Quant:ty 
to  quantity,1  for  in  the  definite  it  is  clear  there  is   perse,  imsno 
nothing  contrary,  as  to  "  two  cubits  "  or  to  "  three," 
or  to  "  superficies,"  or  to  any  thing  of  this  kind,  for  there 
is  no  contrary  to  them  ;  except  indeed  a  man  should  allege 
that  "  much  "  was  contrary  to  "  little,"  or  the  "  great  "  to  the 
"  small."    Of  these  however,  none  is  a  quantity,  but  rather  be- 
longs to  relatives,  since  nothing,  itself  by  itself,  is  described  as 
great  or  small,   but  from  its  being  referred   to 
something  else.    A  mountain,  for  instance,  is  called  ^^n^oimded 
"  little,"  but  a  millet  seed  "  large,"  from  the  fact   upon  the  con- 
of  the  one  being  greater,  but  the  other  less,  in  re-   toyman?  srea' 
spect  of  things  of  the  same  nature,  whence  the 
relation  is  to  something  else,  since  if  each  were  called  "  small " 
or  "great"  of  itself,  the  mountain  would  never  have  been 
called  "  small,"  nor  the  seed  "  large.j    We  say  also  that  there 
are  "  many  "  men  in  a  village,  but  "  few  "  at  Athens,  although 
these  last  are  more  numerous,  and  "  many "  in  a  house,  but 
"  few  "  in  a  theatre,  although  there  is  a  much  larger  number 
in  the  latter.     Besides,  "  two  cubits,"  "  three,"  and  every  thing 
of  the  kind  signify  quantity,  but  "gi'eat  "  or  "  small "  does  not 
signify  quantity,  but   rather  relation,  for   the  "  great "  and 
"  small "  are  viewed  in  reference  to  something  else,  so  as  evi- 
dently to  appear  relatives.     Whether  however  any  one  does, 
or  does  not,  admit  such  things  to  be  quantities,  still  there  is 
no  contrary  to  them,  for  to  that  which  cannot  of 
itself  be  assumed,  but  is  referred  to  another,  how 
can  there  be  a  contrary  ?     Yet  more,  if  "  great "  and  "  small " 
be  contraries,  it  will  happen,  that  the  same  thing, 
at  the  same  time,  receives  contraries,  and  that  the 
same  things  are  contrary  to  themselves,  for  it  happens  that  the 
same  thing  at  the  same  time  is  both  "  great "  and  "  small." 
Something  in  respect  of  this  thing  is  "  small,"  but  the  same,  in 
reference  to  another,  is  "  large,"  so  that  the  same  thing  happens 
at  the  same  time  to  be  both  "great"  and  "small,"  by  which  at 
the  same  moment  it  receives  contraries.     Nothing   12  simuitane- 
however  appears  to  receive  contraries  simultane-   °us  contrariety 
ously,  as  in  the  case  of  substance,  for  this  indeed  injpos 

1  I^tor  rov  ttoctov  nwilioKav  tiviq  to  fi7}Siv  fxfiv  tvavriov,  ttooq  dva- 
rpoTn)v  d'e   tovtov  oil  ^wpci,  Sid  to  Trpo(n\wg  £t?a£ai,  on  ovfii  Ty  ovoiq 
itiv  tvavTiov. — Magent.  Schol.  ed.  Waitz.     Cf.  Metaph.  lib.  ix.  c.  4,  h, 
and  7. 

G 


18  Aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  vi. 

seems  capable  of  contraries,  yet  no  one  is  at  the  same  time  "  sick  " 
and  "  healthy,"  nor  a  thing  "  white  "  and  "  black  "  together, 
neither  does  any  thing  else  receive  contraries  at  one  and  the 
13  same  time^ |   It  happens  also,  that  the  same  things 

are  contrary  to  themselves,  since  if  the  "  great " 
be  opposed  to  the  "  small,"  but  the  same  thing  at  the  same 
time  be  great  and  small,  the  same  thing  would  be  contrary  to 
itself,  but  it  is  amongst  the  number  of  impossibilities,  that  the 
same  thing  should  be  contrary  to  itself,  wherefore  the  great  is 
not  contrary  to  the  small,  nor  the  many  to  the  few,  so  that  even 
if  some  one  should  say  that  these  do  not  belong  to  relatives, 
but  to  quantity,  still  they  will  have  no  contrary. 
H.  The  contra-  The  contrariety  however  of  quantity  seems 
titet'yc°hieflan  especially  to  subsist  about  place,  since  men  admit 
subsistent  in  "  upward  "  to  be  contrary  to  "  downward,"  calling 
space.  t|ae  piace  toward  the  middle  "  downward,"  because 

there  is  the  greatest  distance  from  the  middle,  to  the  extremities 
of  the  world  ; l  they  appear  also  to  deduce  the  definition  of  the 
other  contraries  from  these,  for  they  define  contraries  to  be 
those  things  which,  being  of  the  same  genus,  are  most  distant 
from  each  other. 

is.  Quantity  is  Nevertheless  quantity  does  not  appear  capable 
incapable  of  tie-   of  the  greater  and  the  lessj  as  for  instance  "two 

cubits,"  for  one  thing  is  not  more  "  two  cubits  " 
than  another  ;  neither  in  the  case  of  number,  since  "  three  "  or 
"  five  "  are  not  said  to  be  more  than  "  three  "  or  "  five,"  nei- 
ther "five"  more  "five"  than  "three"  "three;"  one  time 
also  is  not  said  to  be  more  "  time  "  than  another ;  in  short,  of 
none  that  I  have  mentioned  is  there  said  to  be  a  greater  or  a 
less,  wherefore  quantity  is  not  capable  of  the  greater  and  less. 
16.  But  of  Still  it  is  the  especial  peculiarity  of  quantity 

equality  and  to  be  called  "  equal"  and  "unequal,"2  for  each  of 
mequaiy.         ^    akOVe-mentioned   quantities    is   said    to   be 

1  The  "  upward  "  and  "  downward  "  do  not  signify  place,  but  the  pre- 
dicament where,  just  as  "  yesterday  "  and  "  to-day  "  do  not  signify  time, 
but  the  predicament  when.  Simplicius.  Andronicus  also  assents  to  this. 
Compare  the  4th  book  of  Arist.  Physics,  where  he  defines  piace  to  be 
the  boundary  of  that  which  it  contains  ;  the  Pythagoreans,  who  in  words 
agree  with  Aristotle,  in  effect  differ  most  widely  from  him.  Phys.  lib. 
vi.  and  viii. 

2  This  may  be  shown  thus  :  Quantity,  quoad  se,  is  measurable ;  but 
the  measurable  can  be  measured  by  the  same,  or  by  more  or  by  fewer 
measures;  in  the  first  case  therefore,  equal1  ty,  in  the  second,  inequality, 


CHAP.  VII. ]  THE    CATEGORIES.  19 

"equal"  and  "unequal,"  thus  body  is  called  "equal"  and 
"unequal,"  and  number,  and  time,  are  predicated  of  as  "equal  " 
and  "  unequal ; "  likewise  in  the  case  of  the  rest  enumerated, 
each  one  is  denominated  "  equal "  and  "  unequal."  Of  the 
remainder,  on  the  contrary,  such  as  are  not  quantities,  do  not 
altogether  appear  to  be  called  "  equal "  and  "  unequal,"  as  for 
instance,  disposition  is  not  termed  entirely  "equal"  and  "un- 
equal," but  rather  "similar"  and  "dissimilar;"  and  white- 
ness is  not  altogether  "  equal "  and  "  unequal,"  but  rather 
"similar"  and  "dissimilar;"  hence  the  peculiarity  of  quan- 
tity will  especially  consist  in  its  being  termed  "  equal "  and 
"  unequal." 

Chap.  VII.— Of  Relatives? 
Such  things  are  termed  "  relatives,"  which  are    ,   r,  -  ...      . 

.,         ,       °  ,  '.  ~^     1..  Definition  of 

said  to  be  what  they  are,  from  belonging  to  other  relatives,  and 
things,  or  in  whatever  other  way  they  may  be  re-  mstances- 
ferred  to  something  else  ;  thus  "  the  greater"  is  said  to  be  what 
it  is  in  reference  to  another  thing,  for  it  is  called  greater  than 
something  ;  and  "  the  double  "  is  called  what  it  is  in  reference  to 
something  else,  for  it  is  said  to  be  double  a  certain  thing  ;  and  si- 
milarly as  to  other  things  of  this  kind.  Such  as  these  are  of  the 
number  of  relatives,  as  habit,2  disposition,  sense,  knowledge,  po- 
sition, for  all  these  specified  are  said  to  be  what  they  are,  from 
belonging  to  others,  or  however  else  they  are  referrible  to 
another,  and  they  are  nothing  else ;  for  habit  is  said  to  be 
the  habit  of  some  one,  knowledge  the  knowledge  of  something, 
position  the  position  of  somewhat,  and  so  the  rest.  Relatives, 
therefore,  are  such  things,  as  are  said  to  be  what  they  are,  from 
belonging  to  others,  or  which  may  somehow  be  referred  to  an- 
other ;  as  a  mountain  is  called  "great"  in  comparison  with  an- 
other, for  the  mountain  is  called  "great"  in  relation  to  something, 
and  "  like  "  is  said  to  be  like  somewhat,  and  other  things  of  this 

subsists.  Archytas  divides  the  equal  and  unequal  triply,  according  to 
the  three  differences  of  quantity.     Taylor. 

1  Compare  the  divisions  of  relation  given  in  the  Metaphys.  lib.  iv.  c.  15. 

*  This  must  not  be  confounded  with  the  action  of  habit  alluded  to  in 
b.  ii.  c.  2,  of  the  Ethics.  Plotinus  doubts  whether  habit  in  things  re- 
lated be  other  than  a  mere  name.  This  chapter  is  a  thorough  specimen 
of  Aristotelian  prolixity,  of  which,  by  a  slight  change  in  the  Horatiau 
line,  we  may  say, — 

"  Et  facundia  deseret  hunc  et  lucidus  ordo."     Ars  Poet   41. 

c  2 


20  Aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  vit. 

sort,  are  similarly  spoken  of,  in  relation  to  something.  Re- 
clining, station,  sitting,  are  nevertheless  certain  positions,  and 
position  is  a  relative  ;  but  to  recline,  to  stand,  or  to  sit,  are  not 
themselves  positions,  but  are  paronymously  denominated  from 
the  above-named  positions. 

2.  Some  reia-  Yet  there  is  contrariety  in  relatives,  as  virtue 

tives  admit        is  contrary  to  vice,  each  of  them  being  relative, 
and  knowledge  to  ignorance  ; '  but  contrariety  is  not 
inherent  in  all  relatives,  since  there  is  nothing  contrary  to 
double,  nor  to  triple,  nor  to  any  thing  of  the  sort. 

3  Aisod  Relatives   appear,  notwithstanding,  to  receive 

the  more  and  the  less,  for  the  like  and  the  unlike 
are  said  to  be  so,  more  and  less,  and  the  equal  and  the  un- 
equal are  so  called,  more  and  less,  each  of  them  being  a 
relative,  for  the  similar  is  said  to  be  similar  to  something,  and 

4  e.      r        *ne  une(lual>  unequal  to  something.     Not  that  all 

relatives  admit  of  the  more  and  less,  for  double  is 
not  called  more  and  less  double,  nor  any  such  thing,  but  all 

5.  Relatives  relatives  are  styled  so  by  reciprocity,  as  the  servant 
reciprocally       is  said  to  be  servant  of  the  master,  and  the  master, 

master  of  the  servant ;  and  the  double,  double  of 
the  half,  also  the  half,  half  of  the  double,  and  the  greater, 
greater  than  the  less,  and  the  less,  less  than  the  greater.  In 
like  manner  it  happens  as  to  other  things,  except  that  some- 
times they  differ  in  diction  by  case,  as  knowledge  is  said  to 
be  the  knowledge  of  something  knowable,  and  what  is  know- 
able  is  knowable  by  knowledge  :  sense  also  is  the  sense  of 

6.  Except  the  sensible,  and  the  sensible  is  sensible  by  sense, 
where  the  attri-   Sometimes   indeed  they  appear   not  to  recipro- 

butionofthe  .  „     .  ,  J       rr .        ,  ...  - 

relation  is  er-  cate,  if  that  be  not  appropriately  attributed  to 
roneous.  which  relation  is  made,  but  here  he  who  attributes 

errs  ;  for  instance,  a  wing  of  a  bird,  if  it  be  attributed  to  the 
bird,  does  not  reciprocate,  for  the  first  is  not  appropriately 

1  These  are  relatives,  according  to  their  genus,  which  is  habit  in  this 
case.  It  may,  however,  be  inquired  how  Aristotle  afterwards  ranks  sci- 
ence, virtue,  and  their  opposites,  amongst  qualities?  Because  the  same 
thing,  as  he  shows  throughout,  according  to  its  connexion  with  different 
relations,  occupies  often  a  different  predicament.  Hence,  also,  contrariety 
is  only  partly  inherent  in  relatives,  since  they  derive  their  contrariety 
from  the  contrariety  of  their  predicaments  :  thus  in  habit  or  in  quality 
they  receive  contrariety,  but  not  in  the  double  or  triple,  because  quantity 
does  not  receive  it.  To  admit  contraries  therefore,  is  not  the  peculiarity 
of  relatives,  since  contrariety  is  not  in  all  relatives,  nor  in  them  alone, 


CHAP.  VII.]  THE    CATEGORIES.  21 

attributed,  namely  "  wing  "  to  "  bird,"  since  "  wing  "  is  not 
predicated  of  it  so  far  as  it  is  "  bird,"  but  so  far  as  it  is 
"  winged,"  as  there  are  wings  of  many  other  things  which  are 
not  birds,  so  that  if  it  were  appropriately  attributed,  it  would 
also  reciprocate ;  as  "  wing  "  is  the  wing  of  "  a  winged  crea- 
ture," and  "  the  winged  creature  "  is  "  winged  "  by  the  "  wing." 
It  is  sometimes  necessary  perhaps  even  to  invent   . 

7    NgcgssHv  of 

a  name,1  if  there  be  none  at  hand,  for  that  to  sometimes  in- 
which  it  may  be  properly  applied :  e.  g.  if  a  rudder  f^^reulta"6 
be  attributed  to  a  ship,  it  is  not  properly  so  attri- 
buted, for  a  rudder  is  not  predicated  of  a  ship  so  far  as  it  is 
"  ship,"  since  there  are  ships  without  rudders ;  hence  they  do 
not  reciprocate,  inasmuch  as  a  ship  is  not  said  to  be  the  ship 
of  a  rudder.  The  attribution  will  perhaps  be  more  appro- 
priate, if  it  were  attributed  thus,  a  rudder  is  the  rudder  of 
something  ruddered,  or  in  some  other  way,  since  a  name  is 
not  assigned ;  a  reciprocity  also  occurs,  if  it  is  appropriately 
attributed,  for  what  is  ruddered  is  ruddered  by  a  rudder.  So 
also  in  other  things  ;  the  head,  for  example,  will  be  more  ap- 
propriately attributed  to  something  headed,  than  to  animal, 
for  a  thing  has  not  a  head,  so  far  as  it  is  an  animal,  since 
there  are  many  animals  which  have  not  a  head. 

Thus  any  one  may  easily  assume  those  things  to   8  Rule  for  no_ 
which  names  are  not  given,, if  from  those  which   mination  of  re- 
are  first,  he  assigns  names  to  those  others  also,   ciproc 
with   which    they   reciprocate,2    as   in   the    cases    adduced, 
"winged"  from  "wing,"   and   "ruddered"  from  "rudder." 
All  relatives  therefore,  if  they  be  properly  attri-   9  A11  proper 
buted,  are  referred  to  reciprocals,  since  if  they  relatives  reci- 
are  referred  to  something  casual,  and  not  to  that  proc 
to  which  they  relate,  they  will  not  reciprocate.     I  mean,  that 
neither  will  any  one  of  those  things  which  are  admitted  to  be 
referrible  to  reciprocals,  reciprocate,  even  though  names  be 
assigned  to  them,  if  the  thing  be  attributed  to  something  ac- 
cidental, and  not  to  that  to  which  it  has  relation :  for  ex- 

1  Conf.  Top.  i.  5,  1,  also  Anal.  Post,  ii.  7,  2.  Definable  objects  are 
of  two  classes,  producing  a  corresponding  variety  in  the  form  of  defini- 
tion. 1st,  Attributes,  which  include  things  belonging  to  every  other  cate- 
gory but  that  of  substance.  2nd,  Substances,  which  not  existing  in  a  sub- 
ject, but  per  se,  must  be  assumed  before  their  attributes  or  relatives  can  be 
demonstrated.     The  definition  of  an  attribute  is  to  be  found  in  its  cause. 

7  See  Blair's  Lectures  on  Rhetoric,  under  Figurative  Language. 


22  aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  vii. 

ample,  a  servant,  if  he  be  not  attributed  as  the  servant  of  a 
master,  but  of  a  man,  of  a  biped,  or  any  thing  else  of  the  kind, 
will  not  reciprocate,  for  the  attribution  is  not  appropriate. 
If  however  that,  to  which  something  is  referred,  be  appropri- 
ately attributed,  every  thing  else  accidental  being  taken 
away,  and  this  thing  alone  being  left,  to  which  it  is  appropri- 
ately attributed,  it  may  always  be  referred  to  it,  as  "  a 
servant,"  if  he  is  referred  to  "  a  master,"  every  thing  else  ac- 
cidental to  the  master  being  left  out  of  the  question,  (as  the 
being  "  a  biped,"  and  "  capable  of  knowledge,"  and  that  he  is 
"a  man,")  and  his  being  "a  master"  alone,  left,  here  the 
"  servant  "  will  always  be  referred  to  him,  for  a  "  servant " 
is  said  to  be  the  servant  of  a  "  master."  If  again,  on  the 
other  hand,  that  to  which  it  is  at  any  time  referred  is  not  ap- 
propriately attributed,  other  things  being  taken  away,  and 
that  alone  left,  to  which  it  is  attributed,  in  this 

lxiste°ncheaofthe  case  it;  wil1  not  be  referred  to  it.  For  let  a  "  serv- 
one  depends  ant "  be  referred  to  "  man,"  and  a  "  wing  "  to 
vm"  infra,  i"'  "bird,"  and  let  the  being  "  a  master  "  be  taken 
away  from  "  man,"  the  servant  will  no  longer 
refer  to  man,  since  "master"  not  existing,  neither  does  "serv- 
ant "  exist.  So  also  let  "  being  winged  "  be  taken  away  from 
"  bird,"  and  "  wing  "  will  no  longer  be  amongst  relatives,  for 
what  is  "  winged  "  not  existing,  neither  will  "  wing  "  be  the 
wing  of  any  thing.  Hence  it  is  necessary  to  attribute  that, 
to  which  a  thing  is  appropriately  referred,  and  if  indeed  a  name 
be  already  given  to  it,  the  application  is  easy  ;  but  if  no  name  be 
assigned,  it  is  perhaps  necessary  to  invent  one  ;  but  being  thus 
attributed,  it  is  clear  that  all  relatives  are  referred  to  reciprocals^/ 
^  Naturally,  relatives  appear  simultaneous,  and 
by  naturelie-s  ^is  is  true  of  the  generality  of  them,  for  "  double " 
muitaneous,  and  "half"  are  simultaneous,  and  "half"  existing, 
caption™6 '  ' '  double  "  exists,  and  "  a  master"  existing,  the  "  serv- 
ant "  is,  and  the  "  servant "  existing,  the  "master  " 
is,  and  other  things  are  also  like  these.  These  also  are  mutually 
subversive,  for  if  there  is  no  "double"  there  is  no  "half,"  and  no 
"half"  there  is  no  "double"  ;  likewise  as  to  other  things  of  the 
same  kind.  It  does  not  however  appear  to  be  true  of  all  re- 
12  As  science  Stives,  that  they  are  by  nature  simultaneous,  for 
and  its  object,  the  object  of  "  science  "  may  appear  to  be  prior 
apparen  y.        ^o  i(  gcjencej"  smce  for  the  most  part  we  derive 


CHAP.  VIT.J  THE    CATEGORIES.  23 

science  from  things  pre-existing,  as  in  few  things,  if  even  in 
any,  do  we  see  science  and  its  object  originating  together. 
Moreover,  the  object  of  science  being  subverted,  13  Sometimes 
co-subverts  the  science,  but  science  being  sub-  tut  not  always, 
verted,  does  not  co-subvert  the  object  of  science, 
for  there  being  no  object  of  science,  science  itself  becomes 
non-existent,  (since  there  will  be  no  longer  a  science  of  any 
thing) ; 1  but  on  the  contrary,  though  science  does  not  exist, 
there  is  nothing  to  prevent  the  object  of  science  existing.  Thus 
the  quadrature  of  the  circle,  if  it  be  an  object  of  scientific 
knowledge,  the  science  of  it  does  not  yet  exist,  though  it  is  itself 
an  object  of  science  : 2  again,  "  animal "  being  taken  away,  there 
will  not  be  "  science,"  but  still  it  is  possible  for  14  Instance  of 
many  objects  of  science  to  be.  Likewise  also  do  things  pertain- 
things  pertaining  to  sense  subsist,  since  the  sens-  ]  s 
ible  seems  to  be  prior  to  the  sense,  as  the  sensible  being  sub- 
verted co-subverts  sense,  but  sense  does  not  co-subvert  the 
sensible.  For  the  senses  are  conversant  with  body,  and  are  in 
body,  but  the  sensible  being  subverted,  body  also  is  subverted, 
(since  body  is  of  the  number  of  sensibles,)  and  body  not  existing, 
sense  also  is  subverted,  so  that  the  sensible  co-subverts  sense. 
Sense  on  the  other  hand  does  not  co-subvert  the  sensible,  since  if 
animal  were  subverted,  sense  indeed  would  be  subverted,  but  yet 

1  This  is  self-evident,  as  also  that  there  are  some  few  things  in  which 
science  is  the  same  as  its  object,  e.  g.  things  without  matter  are  certainly 
present  at  the  same  time  as  the  intellectual  science  which  abides  in 
energy.  On  the  contrary,  in  the  other  case,  as  Simplicius  observes,  if  in- 
dolence reject  the  knowledge  of  things,  yet  the  things  themselves  remain, 
as  music,  etc.  Vide  also  Brewer's  Introduction  to  the  Ethics,  book  v.,  as 
to  the  position  occupied  by  tTri<jT>ifi.ij  in  the  scheme  of  the  rive  habits.  It 
will  thence  appear  second,  and  correspond  to  deduction  from  certain  prin- 
ciples, the  latter  being  a  subdivision  of  abstract  truth,  thus  : 

Abstract  truth 


Principles  Deductions  from 

voiig  Principles 

I  iTTicrr))/!)] 

« v < 

together    |    crocpia. 

'  Aristotle  selects  this  instance,  as  the  quadrature  of  the  circle  does  not 
appear  from  this,  to  have  been  known  in  his  time,  but  Iamblichus  asserts 
that  it  was  known  to  the  Pythagoreans,  and  Sextus  Pythagoricus  re- 
ceived it  by  succession.  Archimedes  is  stated  to  have  discovered  the 
quadrature  of  the  circle  by  a  line  called  the  line  of  Nicomedes  :  he  himself 
Styled  it  the  quadratrix. 


24  aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  vii. 

the  sensible  will  remain  ;  such  for  instance  as  "body,"  "  warm," 
"  sweet,"  "  bitter,"  and  every  thing  else  which  is  sensible.  Be- 
sides, "  sense  "  is  produced  simultaneously  with  what  is  "  sensi- 
tive," for  at  one  and  the  same  time  "  animal  "  and  "  sense  "  are 
produced,  but  the  "  sensible  "  is  prior  in  existence  to  "  animal " 
or  "  sense,"  for  fire  and  water,  and  such  things  as  animal  con- 
sists of,  are  altogether  prior  to  the  existence  of  animal  or  sense, 
so  that  the  sensible  will  appear  to  be  antecedent  to  sense. 
15  Primary  ^  *s  doubtful  however  whether  no  substance  is 

substance  has  among  the  number  of  relatives,  as  seems  to  be  the 
case,  or  whether  this  happens  in  certain  second  sub- 
stances ;  for  it  is  true  in  first  substances,  since  neither  the 
wholes,  nor  the  parts,  of  first  substances  are  relative.  "  A  cer- 
tain man  "  is  not  said  to  be  a  certain  man  of  something,  nor  "  a 
certain  ox"  said  to  be  a  certain  ox  of  something  ;  and  so  also  with 
respect  to  the  parts,  for  a  "  certain  hand  "  is  not  said  to  be  a  cer- 
tain hand  of  some  one,  but  the  hand  of  some  one  ;  and  some  head 
is  not  said  to  be  a  certain  head  of  some  one,  but  the  head  of  some 
one,  and  in  most  secondary  substances  the  like  occurs.  Thus 
man  is  not  said  to  be  the  man  of  some  one,  nor  an  ox  the  ox 
of  some  one,  nor  the  wood  the  wood  of  some  one,  but  they 
are  said  to  be  the  possession  of  some  one  ;  in  such  things 
therefore,  it  is  evident,  that  they  are  not  included  amongst  re- 
16.  But  some  latives.  In  the  case  of  some  secondary  substances 
secondary  sub-  there  js  a  doubt,  as  "  head,"  is  said  to  be  the  head  of 

stances  seem  to  '  ,         > 

possess  reia-  some  one,  and  "  hand, '  the  hand  ol  some  one,  and  in 
question1  is*6  like  manner,  every  such  thing,  so  that  these  may 
solved  by  an  appear  amongst  the  number  of  relatives.  If  then 
definition  of  e  the  definition  of  relatives  has  been  sufficiently 
™'  "'"iv"' T'-  framed,  it  is  either  a  matter  of  difficulty,  or  of 
impossibility,  to  show  that  no  substance  is  relative ; l  but  if 

1  Plato's  favourite  method  of  definition,  which  however  was  rejected  by 
Speusippus,  was  to  take  a  wide  genus,  and  by  the  addition  of  successive 
differentia,  to  arrive  at  a  complex  notion,  co-extensive  with  the  desired 
definition.  Aristotle,  on  the  other  hand,  to  discover  definition,  employed 
the  inductive  method,  (he  does  not  name  this  however,)  which  consisted 
in  examining  the  several  individuals,  of  which  the  term  to  be  defined  is 
predicable,  and  observing  what  they  had  in  common.  This  will  apply  to 
relatives  and  co-relatives  equally,  and  hence  we  perceive  that,  properly 
speaking,  all  definition  is  an  inquiry  into  attributes.  Every  substance 
definable  must  be  a  species,  every  attribute  a  property.  Vide  Scholia. 
Edinburgh  Review,  No.  cxv.  p.  236.     Pacius  on  Anal.  Post,  11,  13,  21. 


CHAP.  VII.]  THE    CATEGORIES.  25 

the  definition  has  not  been  sufficiently  framed,  but  those 
things  are  relatives,  whose  substance  is  the  same,  as  consists 
with  a  relation,  after  a  certain  manner,  to  a  certain  thing  ; 
somewhat,  perhaps,  in  reply  to  this,  may  be  stated.  The  ^ 
former  definition,  however,  concurs  with  all  relatives,  yet  it 
is  not  the  same  thing,  that  their  being,  consists  in  relation, 
and  that  being  what  they  are,  they  are  predicated  17.  one  reia- 
of  other  things.     Hence  it  is  clear,  that  he  who   ,tive  bei"? 

i  i      •  1    A    •  .    1  mi      1        i  known,  the  co- 

knows  any  one  relative,  definitely,  will  also  know  relative  can  be 
what  it  is  referred  to,  definitely.  ( Wherefore  also  known- 
from  this  it  is  apparent,  that  if  one  knows  this  particular 
thing  to  be  among  relatives,  and  if  the  substance  of  relatives 
is  the  same,  as  subsisting  in  a  certain  manner,  with  reference 
to  something,  he  will  also  know  that,  with  reference  to  which, 
this  particular  thing,  after  a  certain  manner,  subsists  ;  for  if,  in 
short,  he  were  ignorant  of  that,  with  reference  to  which,  this 
particular  thing,  after  a  certain  manner,  subsists,  neither  would 
he  know,  whether  it  subsists,  after  a  certain  manner,  with  re- 
ference to  something.     And  in  singulars,  indeed,    ,„  „.     , 

,..  .,  n       •/>  1  -i^^i         18- Singulars. 

this  is  evident ;  lor  11  any  one  knows  definitely, 
that  this  thing  is  "  double,"  he  will  also  forthwith  know  that, 
definitely,  of  which  it  is  the  double,  since  if  he  knows  not  that 
it  is  the  double,  of  something  definite,  neither  will  he  know 
that  it  is  "  double,"  at  all.  So  again,  if  a  man  knows  this 
thing,  to  be  more  beautiful  than  something  else,  he  muse 
straightway  and  definitely  know  that,  than  which,  it  is  more 
beautiful.  (Wherefore,  he  will  not  indefinitely  know,  that  this, 
is  better,  than  that  which  is  worse,  for  such  is  opinion  and  not 
science,  since  he  will  not  accurately  know  that  it  is  better 
than  something  worse,  as  it  may  so  happen  that  there  is 
nothing  worse  than  it,  j  whence  it  is  necessarily  evident,  that 
whoever  definitely  knows  any  relative,  also  definitely  knows 
that,  to  which   it   is   referred.       It   is   possible,    ,„  _ 

19.  lhc  con- 

notwithstanding,    to    know   definitely    what   the   verse  true  of 
head,  and  the  hand,  and  every  thing  of  the  sort   ss^edsary  sub 
are,  which  are  substances ;  but  it  is  not  necessary 
to  know  that  to  which  they  are  referred,  since  it  is  not  neces- 
sary definitely  to  know  whose,  is  the  head,  or  whose,  is  the 
hand ;  thus  these  will  not  be  relatives,  but  if  these  be  not 
relatives,  we  may  truly  affirm  no  substance  to  be  among  re- 
latives.    It  is,  perhaps,  difficult  for  a  man  to  assert  assuredly 


26  aristotle's  organon.  [chap,  vin, 

any  thing  of  such  matters,  who  has  not  frequently  considered 
them,  yet  to  have  submitted  each  of  them  to  inquiry,  is  not 
without  its  use.1 

Chap.  VIII. —  Of  the  Quale  and  of  Quality ? 

1.  Quality  and  By  quality,  I  mean  that,  according  to  which,  cer- 
its species;  the   ta;n  things,  are  said  to  be,  what  they  are.    Quality, 

latter  of  four  ° .  .  J    .  ,\ 

kinds.  however,  is  among  those  things  which  are  predi- 

dtspo^ftion— d  cate(i  multifariously  ;  hence  one  species  of  quality 
these  ex-  is  called  "habit"  and  "disposition,"    but  habit, 

p  ame  .  differs  from  disposition,  in  that  it  is  a  thing  more 

lasting  and  stable.3  Of  this  kind  too,  are  both  the  sciences 
and  the  virtues,4  for  science  appears  to  rank  among  those 
things,  which  continue  more  stable,  and  are  hardly  removed, 
even  when  science  is  but  moderately  attained,  unless  some 
great  change  should  occur  from  disease,  or  from  something 
of  the  sort ;  so  also  virtue,  as  justice,  temperance,  and  so 
forth,  does  not  appear  capable  of  being  moved  or  changed  with 
facility.  But  those  are  termed  dispositions,  which  are  easily 
moved  and  quickly  changed,  as  heat,  cold,  disease,  health,  and 
such  things ;  or  a  man  is  disposed,  after  a  manner,  accord- 
ing to  these,  but  is  rapidly  changed,  from  hot  becoming  cold, 
and  from  health  passing  to  disease,  and  in  like  manner  as  to 
other  tilings,  unless   some  one   of  these  qualities  has,  from 

1  Cf.  Metaph.  lib.  iv.  c.  15. 

2  JloioTrjg.  Def.  "  That  which  imparts  what  is  apparent  in  matter,  and 
what  is  the  object  of  sense."  Taylor's  Explanation  of  Aristotelian  Terms. 
See  also  Metaphys.  lib.  iv.  c.  14,  19,  and  20,  Leip.  The  distinction  in 
the  text  has  been  remarked  upon,  as  exemplifying  Aristotle's  passion  for 
definition,  but  it  would  be  more  correct  to  remember  that  it  was  perhaps 
less  his  inclination  than  his  judgment,  which  induced  him  to  lay  down 
strict  notions  of  verbal  definition  primarily,  knowing  that  the  thing  signi- 
fied, or  idea,  could  never  hold  its  proper  position  in  the  mind,  if  any  doubt 
existed  as  to  the  meaning  of  the  term  or  verbal  symbol  of  it,  ab  origine. 
It  is  a  great  pity  that  modern  controversialists  so  frequently  neglect  this. 

3  Cf.  Ethics,  book  ii.  ch.  5,  and  book  ii.  ch.  1.  In  the  latter  place, 
Aristotle  shows  that  moral  virtue  arises  from  habit,  in  opposition  to  Plato, 
who  taught  that  the  virtues  were  not  produced  by  learning  or  nature,  but 
were  divinely  bestowed.  Aristotle's  opinion  resembled  Locke's,  in  the  de- 
nial of  innate  ideas,  the  soul  having  nothing  within  it  but  inclination,  rd 
TTHpvKoe.  The»student  will  profitably  refer  here  to  Bishop  Butler's  Analogy, 
on  the  growth  of  mental  habits.     Anal,  part  i.  ch.  5.    Bohn's  Stand.  Lib. 

4  So  Cicero,  de  Off.  lib.  iii.,  connects  these  two,  "  temperantia  est 
scientia."     See  also  Montaigne's  Essays,  ch.  xl.  b.  i.,  and  ch.  ii.  b.  iii. 


CHAP.  VIII.]  THE    CATEGORIES.  27 

length  of  time,  become  natural,  immovable,  or  at  least  dif- 
ficult to  be  moved,  in  which  case  we  may  term  it  a  habit. 
But  it  is  evident  that  those  ought  to  be  called  habits,  which  are 
more  lasting,  and  are  with  greater  difficulty  removed,  for  those 
persons  who  do  not  very  much  retain  the  dogmas  of  science,  but 
are  easily  moved,  are  said  not  to  possess  a  scientific  habit, 
although  they  are  in  some  manner  disposed  as  to  science, 
either  worse  or  better  ;  so  that  habit  differs  from  disposition 
in  the  one  being  easily  removed,  but  the  former  is  more  lasting, 
and  less  easily  removed.  Habits  are  dispositions  also,1  but 
dispositions  not  necessarily  habits,  for  those  who  have  habits 
are  also,  after  a  manner,  disposed  according  to  them,  but  those 
who  are  disposed  are  not  altogether  possessed  of  the  habit^ 

Another    kind    of  quality  is,  that,    according   2nd  species  of 
to  which,  we  sav  that  men  are  prone  to  pugilism,   quality,  that 

J  ill  i-  .        which  compre- 

or  to  the  course,  or  to  health,  or  to  disease,  in  hends  the  fa- 
short,  whatever  things  are  spoken  of  according  to  culties- 
natural  power,  or  weakness  ;  for  each  of  these  is  not  denomi- 
nated from  being  disposed  after  a  certain  manner,  but  from 
having  a  natural  power  or  inability  of  doing  something  easily, 
or  of  not  suffering  ;  thus,  men  are  called  pugilistic,  or  fitted 
for  the  course,  not  from  being  disposed  after  a  certain  man- 
ner, but  from  possessing  a  natural  power  of  doing  something 
easily.  Again,  they  are  said  to  be  healthy,  from  possessing  a 
natural  power  of  not  suffering  easily  from  accidents,  but  to  be 
diseased,  from  possessing  a  natural  incapacity  to  resist  suffer- 
ing easily  from  accidents  :  similarly  to  these,  do  hard  and  soft 
subsist,  for  that  is  called  "hard"  which  possesses  the  power 
of  not  being  easily  divided,  but  "  soft,"  that  which  has  an  impo- 
tence as  to  this  same  thincr. 

The  third  kind  of  quality  consists  of  passive  qua-    3rd  Passive 
lities  and  passions,  and  such  are  sweetness,  bitter-   qualities. 

1  The  "H0o£  signifies   the  habitual  disposition  or  "  humour,"  as  in 
Every  Man  out  of  his  Humour,  by  Ben  Jonson. 

"When  some  one  peculiar  quality 

Doth  so  possess  a  man,  that  it  doth  draw 

All  his  affects,  his  spirits,  and  his  powers, 

In  thoir  confluctions,  all  to  run  one  way — 

This  may  be  truly  said  to  be  a  humour." 
Vide  Aristotle's  Rhetoric,  (Bonn's  Class.  Lib.).     And  again,  Coriolanus, 
act  iii.  scene  2,     — Away  my  disposition,  and  possess  me 

Some  harlot's  spirit ! 
Or,  act  iii.  sc.  1,  "  Men:  His  nature,  is  too  noble  for  the  world,"  etc. 


28  ARISTOTLE;S    ORGANON.  [CHAP.  VIII. 

ness,  sourness,  and  all  their  affinities,  besides  warmth,  and  cold- 
ness, and  whiteness,  and  blackness.  Now  that  these  are  qualities, 
is  evident  from  their  recipients  being  called  from  them,  "qua- 
lia," '  as  honey  from  receiving  sweetness,  is  said  to  be  sweet,  and 
the  body  white,  from  receiving  whiteness ;  in  like  manner  in 
other  things.  They  are  called  passive  qualities,2  not  from  the  re- 
cipients of  the  qualities  suffering  any  thing,  for  neither  is  honey 
said  to  be  sweet  from  suffering  any  thing,  nor  any  thing  else  of 
such  a  kind. "  In  like  manner  to  these  are  heat  and  cold  called 
passive  qualities,  not  from  the  recipients  themselves  suffering 
any  thing,  but  because  each  of  the  above-mentioned  qualities 
produces  passion  in  the  senses,  they  are  denominated  passive 
qualities  ;  for  as  sweetness,  produces  a  certain  passion  in  the 
taste,  and  warmth,  in  the  touch,  so  also  do  the  rest.  Whiteness, 
1  Exception  in  an<^  blackness,  and  other  colours  are,  on  the  con- 
the  case  of  co-  trary,  not  called  passive  qualities  in  the  same  man- 
ner with  the  above-mentioned,  but  from  themselves 
being  produced  from  passion ;  for  that  many  changes  of  co- 
lours spring  from  passion  is  evident,  since  when  a  man  blushes 
he  becomes  red,  and  when  frightened,  pale,  and  so  every  thing 
of  this  sort^  Whence  also  if  a  man  naturally  suffers  a  passion 
of  this  nature,  he  will  probably  have  a  similar  colour,  since  the 
disposition  which  is  now  produced  about  the  body  when  he 
blushes,  may  also  be  produced  in  the  natural  constitution,  so 
as  that  a  similar  colour  should  naturally  arise.  Whatever 
such  symptoms   then   originate   from  certain  passions  diffi- 

1  Simplicius  doubts  whether  the  same  thing  is  signified  by  quale,  and 
quality  :  probably  the  latter  signifies  the  peculiarity  itself,  but  quale  that 
which  participates  in  the  peculiarity,  as  in  the  examples  given  above.  As 
to  the  term  "  quality,"  Plato  in  his  Thesetetus  insinuates  that  he  was 
the  author  of  it,  and  indeed  some  ancient  philosophers,  as  Antisthenes, 
subverted  certain  qualities,  and  allowed  only  the  subsistence  of  qualia, 
which  they  deemed  incorporeal.  The  Stoics,  on  the  contrary,  thought 
the  qualities  of  incorporeal  natures  incorporeal,  and  of  bodies,  corporeal. 
Simplicius  defines  qualities — "  powers,  active,  yet  not  so,  primarily,  nor 
alone." 

2  It  may  perhaps  seem  strange  that  Aristotle  distinguishes  passions  and 
passive  qualities  by  the  same  characteristics  as  he  has  before  used  about 
habit  and  disposition ;  but  it  may  be  replied,  that  here  he  considers  the 
passions  and  passive  qualities  which  by  nature  are  easily  or  hardly  re- 
moved. Heat,  so  far  as  it  disposes  a  subject,  is  a  disposition ;  so  far  as 
that  disposition  is  permanent,  is  a  habit ;  if  it  be  superficially  effected  by  an 
agent,  it  is  called  a  passion,  and  so  far  as  the  passion  is  produced  perma- 
nently and  intrinsically,  it  is  called  passive  quality.     Taylor. 


CHAP.  VIII.]  THE    CATEGORIES.  29 

cult  to  be  removed  and  permanent  are  called  passive  qualities. 
For  whether  in  the  natural  constitution,  paleness,  or  blackness, 
be  produced,  they  are  called  qualities,  (for  according  to  them 
we  are  called  "  quales  ;")  or  whether  through  long  disease  or 
heat,  or  any  such  thing,  paleness  or  blackness  happens,  nei- 
ther are  easily  removed,  or  even  remain  through  life,  these  are 
called  qualities,  for  in  like  manner,  we  are  called  "  quales  "  in 
respect  of  them.     Notwithstanding,  such  as  are 
produced  from  things  easily  dissolved,  and  quickly   j^  ™"e  may 
restored,  are  called  passions,1   and  not  qualities, 
for  men  are  not  called  "  quales"  in  respect  of  them,  since  neither 
is  he  who  blushes,  in  consequence  of  being  ashamed,  called  red, 
nor  he  who  turns  pale,  from  fear,  called  pale,  they  are  rather 
said  to  have  suffered  something,  so  that  such  things  are  called 
passions,  but  not  qualities.     Like  these  also  are   3   Also  affec_ 
passive  qualities,  and  passions  denominated  in  the   tions  of  the 
soul.    For  such  things  as  supervene  immediately 
upon  birth  from  certain  passions  difficult  of  removal,  are  called 
qualities ;  as  insanity,  anger,  and  such  things,  for  men   ac- 
cording to  these  are  said  to  be  "  quales,"  that  is,  wrathful  and 
insane.     So  also  as  many  other  mutations  as  are  not  natural, 
but  arise  from  certain  other  symptoms,  and  are  with  difficulty 
removed,  or  even  altogether  immovable,  such  are  qualities, 
for  men  are  called  "  quales  "  in  respect  of  them.     Those  which, 
on  the  other  hand,  arise  from  things  easily  and  rapidly  restored, 
are  called  passions,  as  for  instance,  where  one  being  vexed 
becomes  more  wrathful,  for  he  is  not  called  wrathful  who  is 
more  wrathful  in  a  passion  of  this  kind,  but  rather  he  is  said 
to  have  suffered  something,  whence  such  things  are  called 
passions,  but  not  qualities.2 

The  fourth  kind  of  quality  is  figure  and  the  form,  4th  species  of 
which  is  about  every  thing,  besides  rectitude  and  quality— form 
curvature,  and  whatever  is  like  them,  for  accord-  an  gure' 
ing  to  each  of  these  a  thing  is  called  "  quale."  Thus  a  tri- 
angle or  a  square  is  said  to  be  a  thing  of  a  certain  quality, 
also  a  straight  line  or  a  curve,  and  every  thing  is  said  to  be 
"  quale "  according  to  form.  The  rare  and  the  dense,  the 
rough  and  the  smooth,  may  appear  to  signify  a  certain  quality, 

1  Cf.   Ethics,  b.  ii.  ch.  5;  also  Metaphys.  lib.  iv.  ch.  21;  where  the 
same  examples  of  inanimate  objects  are  given. 

*  Ethics,  book  ix.  ch.  8.     The  being  loved  is  like  something  passive. 


30  Aristotle's  organon.  [chap,  vm, 

but  probably  these  are  foreign  from  the  division  of  quality,  as 
each  appears  rather  to  denote  a  certain  position  of  parts.  For 
a  thing  is  said  to  be  "  dense,"  from  having  its  parts  near  each 
other,  but  "rare,"  from  their  being  distant  from  each  olher,  and 
"  smooth,"  from  its  parts  lying  in  some  respect  in  a  right  line, 
but  "  rough,"  from  this  part,  rising,  and  the  other,  falling. 
5.  Things  call-  There  may  perhaps  appear  to  be  some  other 
nymousiy  from  rnode  of  quality,  but  those  we  have  enumerated 
these  qualities.    are  most  commonly  called  so. 

The  above-named  therefore  are  qualities,  but  "  qualia  "  are 
things  denominated  paronymously  according  to  them,  or  in  some 
other  manner  from  them ;  most  indeed  and  nearly  all  of  them 
are  called  paronymously,1  as  "a  white  man"  from  "whiteness," 
"  a  grammarian "  from  "grammar,"  a  "just  man  " from  "justice," 
and  similarly  of  the  rest.  Still  in  some,  from  no  names  having 
been  given  to  the  qualities,  it  is  impossible  that  they  should 
be  called  paronymously  from  them  ;  for  instance,  a  "  racer " 
or  "  pugilist,"  so  called  from  natural  power,  is  paronymously 
denominated  from  no  quality,  since  names  are  not  given  to 
those  powers  after  which  these  men  are  called  "quales,"  as 
they  are  given  to  sciences,  according  to  which  men  are  said 
to  be  pugilists  or  wrestlers  from  disposition,  for  there  is  said 
to  be  a  pugilistic  and  palaestric  science,  from  which  those  dis- 
posed to  them  are  paronymously  denominated  "quales." 
Sometimes  however,  the  name  being  assigned,  that  which  is 
called  "  quale  "  according  to  it,  is  not  denominated  parony- 
mously, as  from  virtue,  a  man  is  called  worthy,  for  he  is  called 
worthy,  from  possessing  virtue,  but  not  paronymously  from 
virtue ;  this  however  does  not  often  happen,  wherefore  those 
things  are  called  "  qualia,"  which  are  paronymously  denomin- 
ated from  the  above-mentioned  qualities,  or  which  are  in  some 
other  manner  termed  from  them.2 

1  Vide  supra,  Cat.  i.  Massinger's  employment,  of  the  very  word, 
we  are  now  discussing,  presents  a  peculiar  difficulty,  in  establishing  the 
paronymous  or  denominative  relation.  In  the  Roman  Actor,  act  i.  scene 
3,  and  also  in  the  Picture,  act  ii.  scene  1,  the  word  quality  is  limited  to 
actors  and  their  profession.  See  Gifford's  notes  on  Massinger.  In  fact, 
most  of  our  ancient  dramatists  confined  the  word  chiefly  to  histrionic 
performers. 

a  The  name  "  conjugata  "  is  more  properly  applied  to  derivatives  from 
the  same  primitive,  as  sapiens,  sapienter,  sapientia  ;   the  avaToixcc  of  Aris 
totle.     Cf.  Topics  ii.  9,  1.     Cic.  Top.  c.  ih. 


CHAP.  VIII.]  THE    CATEGORIES.  31 

In  quality,  there  is  also  contrariety,1  as  justice 

t  1 .      •    •      f  J        uv  j.     1.1      i        6-  Quality 

is  contrary  to  injustice,  and  whiteness  to  black-   sometimes  sus. 
ness,  and  the  like;  also  those  things  which  sub-   fePt.ible  °f  con- 

7  .  °  trariety. 

sist  according  to  them  are  termed  qualia,  as  the 
unjust  to  the  just,  and  the  white  to  the  black.     This  however 
does  not  happen  in  all  cases,  for  to  the  yellow,  or  the  pale,  or 
such  like  colours,  though  they  are  qualities,  there  is  no  con- 
trary.2    Besides,  if  one  contrary  be  a  quality,  the  other,  will 
also   be   a  quality,    and   this   is    evident    to    any   one    con- 
sidering  the  other  categories.     For  instance,  if 
justice  be  contrary  to  injustice,  and  justice  be  a   trary  be  a  quale  ' 
quality,  then  injustice  will  also  be  a  quality,  for   o»e  other  will 
none  of  the  other  categories  accords  with  injustice, 
neither  quantity,  nor  relation,  nor  where,  nor  in   short   any 
thing  of  the  kind,  except  quality,  and  the  like  also  happens  as 
to  quality  in  the  other  contraries. 

Qualia  also  admit  the  more  and  the  less,3  as  one  thing  is 
said  to  be  more  or  less  "  white  "  than  another,  and  one  more 
and  less  "just"  than  another  ;  the  same  thing  also   8  It  can  also 
itself  admits  accession,  for  what  is  "  white,"  can  be-   admit  degree. 
^ome  more,  "white."    This  however,  does  not  hap- 
pen with  all,  but  with  most  things,  for  some  one  may  doubt 
whether  justice,  can  be  said  to  be  more  or  less  justice,  and  so 
also  in  other  dispositions,  since  some  doubt  about  such,  and  as- 
sert that  justice  cannot  altogether  be  called  more  and  less,  than 
justice,  nor  health  than  health,  but  they  say,  that  one  man  has 
less  health,  than  another,  and  one  person  less  justice,  than  an- 
other, and  so  also  of  the  grammatical  and  other  dispositions. 
Still  the  things  which  are  denominated  according  to  these,  do 
without  question  admit  the  more  and  the  less,  for  one  man  is  said 

1  See  below,  Cat.  xi.  5. 

-  Repugnance  is  not  synonymous  with  contrariety,  e.  g.  red  and  blue 
are  repugnant,  but  not  opposed.  Archytas  says,  "  Certain  contraries  are 
conjoined  to  quality,  as  if  it  received  a  certain  contrariety  and  privation." 

3  Here  he  evidently  means  qualities  by  qualia,  as  the  examples  indi- 
cate. There  were  four  opinions  entertained,  upon  the  admission  by  qualia, 
of  degree.  Plotinus,  and  the  Platonists,  asserted  that  all  qualia,  and  qua- 
lities alike,  received  the  greater  and  the  less  ;  others,  limited  intension,  and 
remission,  to  the  participants  ;  the  Stoics  avowed  that  the  virtues  are  inca- 
pable of  either ;  and  the  fourth  opinion,  which  Porphyry  opposes,  allows 
degree,  to  material,  but  denies  it,  to  immaterial,  and  self-subsistent,  qua- 
lities. Vide  Simp,  in  Catego.  Iamb.  Opera.  Aristotle,  below,  seems  tc 
refer  to  the  second,  of  these  opinions. 


32  Aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  vm. 

to  be  more  grammatical,  than  another,  and  more  healthy,  and 
more  iust,  and  similarly  in  other  things.     Tri- 

Form  incapable  1  j  ,11  i  1 

of  degree.  (Cf.  angle  and  square  appear  nevertheless  incapable 
w^ateiy,  b.  ii.  0f  ^he  more,  as  also  every  other  figure,  since  those 
things  which  receive  the  definition  of  a  triangle, 
and  of  a  circle,  are  all  alike  triangles  or  circles,  but  of  things 
which  do  not  receive  the  same  definition,  none  can  be  said  to 
be  more  such,  than  another,  as  a  square,  is  not  more  a  cir- 
cle, than  an  oblong,  for  neither  of  them  admits  the  definition 
of  the  circle.  In  a  word,  unless  both  receive  the  definition  of 
the  thing  propounded,  one  cannot  be  said  to  be  more  so  and  so, 
than  another,  wherefore  all  qualities  do  not  admit  the  more  and 
the  less. 

Of  the  above-mentioned  particulars  then,  no 
perVyo/quaHty  one  *s  peculiar  to  quality,  but  things  are  said  to 
that  similitude    he  similar,  and  dissimilar,  in  respect  of  qualities 

is  predicated  in       ■,  n  ....  ...  ...  , 

respect  of  it.       alone,  lor  one  thing  is  not  like  another  in  respect 
of  any  thing  else,  than  so  far  as  it  is  quale,  so 
that  it  will  be  peculiar  to  quality,  that  the  like  and  the  unlike 
should  be  termed  so  in  respect  of  it.1 

Yet  we  need  not  be  disturbed  lest  any  one  should  say  that, 
10  r  1  t  proposing  to  speak  of  quality,  we  co-enumerate 
objection— that  many  things  which  are  relatives,  for  we  said  that 
position  are1S"  habits  and  dispositions  are  among  the  number  of  re- 
reckoned  latives,  and  nearly  in  all  such  things  the  genera  are 
tiveTas  weifas  called  relatives,  but  not  one  of  the  singulars.  Sci- 
amongst  qua-  ence,  for  example,  although  it  is  a  genus,  is  said  to 
be  what  it  is,  with  respect  to  something  else,  for  it  is 
said  to  be  the  science  of  a  certain  thing,  but  of  singulars  not 
one  is  said  to  be  what  it  is,  with  reference  to  something  else, 
as  neither  grammar  is  said  to  be  the  grammar  of  something, 
nor  music  the  music  of  something.  But  even  perhaps  these, 
are  called  relatives,  according  to  genus,  as  grammar  is  said  to 
be  the  science  of  something,  not  the  grammar  of  something, 
and  music  the  science  of  something,  not  the  music  of  some- 

1  If  impression  and  character  produce  similitude,  and  quality  consists 
in  character,  it  will  justly  have  its  peculiarity  according  to  the  similar 
and  dissimilar.  Archytas  observes,  "  The  peculiarity  of  quality  is  the  si- 
milar and  the  dissimilar  ;  for  we  say  that  all  those  things  are  similar 
in  colour  which  have  the  same  colour,  and  the  same  idea  of  character; 
but  those  are  dissimilar  which  subsist  in  a  contrary  manner." 


CIIA.P.  IX."1  THi:    CATEGORIES.  33 

thing ;  so  that  singulars  are  not  of  the  number  of  Relatives. 
Still,  we  are  called  quales  from  singulars,1  for 
these  we  possess,  as  we  are  called  scientific  from   not  included 
assessing  certain  singular  sciences  ;  so  that  these   ta™ecsnfclf ^tivs 
nay  be  singular    qualities,   according   to   which   Logic,  de  Divi- 
de are  sometimes  denominated  quales,  but  they 
ire  not  relatives  ;  besides,  if  the  same  thing  should  happen  to 
be  both  a  particular  quality  and  a  relative,  there  is  no  absurdity 
in  its  enumeration  under  both  genera. 

Chap.  IX.     Of  Action,  Passion,  and  the  other  categories  of 
Position  :    When :    Where  :  and  Possessio?i. 

Action  and  Passion  admit  contrariety,  and  the 
more  and  the  less,  for  to  make  warm,  is  contrary  pas^f0tn°admit 
to  making  cold  ;  to  be  warm,  contrary  to  the  being   contrariety  and 
cold,  to  be  pleased,  contrary  to  being  grieved ;  so 
that  they  admit  contrariety.  They  are  also  capable  of  the  more 
and  the  less,  for  it  is  possible  to  heat,  more  and  less,  to  be 
heated,  more  and  less,  and  to  be  grieved,  more  and  less  ;  where- 
fore, to  act,  and  to  suffer,  admit  the  more  and  less,  and  so  much 
may  be  said  of  these.    T5ut  we  have  spoken  of  the  being  situ- 
ated in  our  treatment  of  relatives,2  to  the  effect  that  it  is 
paronymously  denominated,  from  positions  :  as  re-   2  Reca 
gards  the  other  categories,  when,  where,  and  to   tion  of  the  other 
have,  nothing  else  is  said  of  them,  than  what  was   cateeones- 

1  ralg  Ka9'  tKaara,  etc.  It  may  be  useful  here  to  give  a  general  defin- 
ition of  the  several  meanings  applied  by  Aristotle  to  peculiar  uses  of  the 
preposition  as  regards  relative  action  and  relation.  At'  6,  on  account  of 
which,  then  signifies— the  final  cause ;  Si'  6v  through  which — the  instru- 
mental cause  ;  s?  bv  or  iv  </7,  from  or  in  which — the  material  cause ; 
KaQ'  6 — according  to  which — form  is  thus  denominated ;  7rpoc  o,  with  re- 
lation to  which — or  the  paradeigmatic  cause ;  and  v(j>'  6v,  by  which — the 
demiurgic  or  fabricative  cause.  Cf.  Top.  lib.  iv.  c.  15,  et  seq.  Taylor 
makes  one  continual  mistake  in  the  translation  of  Ka9'  tKaara,  by  ren- 
dering it  "  particular,"  whereas  the  latter  is  "  iv  fitpu."  Buhle,  on  the 
contrary,  is  correct  in  this  translation  throughout. 

2  Aristotle  here  refers  the  reader  to  the  category  of  relation,  but  as  re- 
gards the  opinion  entertained  of  the  remaining  categories,  Porphyry  and 
lamblichus  consider  them  as  accessorial  relatives;  e.  g.  "  When  "  and 
"  where"  are  not,  per  se,  place  and  time,  but  when  these  two  latter  exist 
primarily,  the  former  accede  to  them.  Thus  also  "  having"  signifies  some- 
thing distinct  from  the  existing  thing,  at  the  same  time  that  it  exists  with  it. 
Upon  the  reduction  of  the  latter  six  categories  to  relation,  see  Hamilton 
on  lieid,  p.  688 ;  also  St.  Hilaire's  Translation,  Preface,  p.  08,  et  acq. 

» 


34  ARISTOTLE'S    ORGANON.  [  CHAP.  X. 

mentioned  at  first,  because  they  are  evident ;  e.  g.  that  "to  have," 
signifies  to  be  shod,  to  be  armed  ;  "where,"  as  in  the  Lycreum, 
in  the  Forum,  and  the  rest  which  are  spoken  of  these.  Of 
the  proposed  genera  therefore,  suflicient  has  been  stated. 

Chap.  X. —  Of  Opposites* 

i  Opposites  WE  must  now  speak  of  opposites,  in  how  many 
are  of  four         ways  opposition  takes  place.)   One  thing  then  is 

said  to  be  opposed  to  another  in  four  ways,  either 
as  relative,  or  as  contrary,  or  as  privation  and  habit,  or  as 
affirmation  and  negation.  Thus  speaking  summarily,  each 
thing  of  this  kind  is  opposed,  relatively,  as  "  the  double  "  to 
"  the  half,"  contrarily,  as  "  evil "  to  "  good,"  privatively  and 
habitually,  as  "  blindness  "  and  "  sight,"  affirmatively  and  ne- 
gatively, as  "  he  sits,"  "  he  does  not  sit." 

Whatever  things  then  are  relatively  opposed,  are 
posufontive  °P    sa^ to  be  what  they  are  with  reference  to  opposites, 

or  are  in  some  manner  referred  to  them,  as  "  the 
double  of  the  half,"  is  said  to  be  what  it  is,  with  reference  to 
something  else,  for  it  is  said  to  be  the  double  of  something  ;  and 
"  knowledge  "  is  opposed  relatively  to  the  object  of  knowledge, 
and  is  said,  to  be  what  it  is,  in  reference  to  what  may  be 
known,  and  what  may  be  known,  is  said  to  be  what  it  is,  in 
reference  to  an  opposite,  namely,  "  knowledge,"  for  "  the  ob- 
ject of  knowledge  "  is  said  to  be  so,  to  something,  namely,  to 
"knowledge." 

1  For  a  brief  exposition  of  this  chapter,  the  reader  is  referred  to  the 
nature  and  laws  of  logical  opposition  in  necessary,  impossible,  and  con- 
tingent matter,  given  in  Aldrich,  Huyshe,  Whately,  Hill,  and  Man- 
sel.  It  will  be  remembered  however  that  he  here  speaks  of  the  opposi- 
tion of  terms,  the  rules  for  the  opposition  of  propositions  being  more 
especially  considered  in  the  Interpretation  :  still  a  reference  to  that  treatise, 
as  well  as  to  the  authors  cited  above,  will  be  useful,  as  elucidating  the 
grounds  on  which  all  logical  opposition  is  founded.  Archytas  (says 
Simplicius)  does  not  omit,  but  seems  to  have  more  accurately  explained 
the  differences  of  contraries  adduced  by  Aristotle.  He  says  :  Of  contra- 
ries, some  are  in  the  genera  of  genera,  as  good  and  evil,  the  first  being  the 
genus  of  the  virtues,  the  second  of  the  vices  :  some  again  in  the  genera  of 
species,  as  virtue  to  vice,  the  first  being  the  genus  of  prudence,  temperance, 
etc. ;  the  other  of  imprudence,  intemperance :  lastly,  some  in  species,  as 
fortitude  to  timidity,  etc. :  but  he  adds,  "  there  is  nothing  to  prevent  the 
contraries  of  genera  being  reduced  under  one  genus,  as  gcod  and  evil 
unJer  quality." 


CHAP.  X.]  THE    CATEGORIES.  35 

Things  therefore  relatively  opposed  are  said  to  be,  what 
they  are,  with  reference  to  opposites,  or  in  whatever  manner, 
they  are  referrible  to  each  other,  but  those  which 
are  opposed  as  contraries,  are  by  no  means,  said  opposulon17 
to  be  what  they  are,  with  reference  to  each  other, 
but  are  said  to  be  contrary  to  each  other,  for  neither  is 
"good"  said  to  be  the  "good"  of  "evil,"  but  the  contrary  of 
eviL  nor  is  "white,"  denominated  the  "  white  "  of  "black," 
but  its  contrary,  so  that  these  oppositions  differ  from  each 
other.  Such  contraries  however,  as  are  of  that  kind,  that  one 
of  them  must  necessarily  be  in  those  things,  in  which  it  can 
naturally  be,  or  of  which  it  is  predicated,  these  have  nothing 
intermediate ;  but  in  the  case  of  those,  in  which  it  is  not 
necessary,  that  one  should  be  inherent,  there  is  something 
intermediate.  For  instance,  health  and  disease  may  na- 
turally subsist  in  the  body  of  an  animal,  and  it  is  necessary 
that  one,  should  be  therein,  either  disease,  or  health ;  the  odd 
and  even  are  also  predicated  of  number,  and  one  of  the  two, 
either  the  odd  or  the  even,  must  necessarily  be  in  number,  yet 
there  is  nothing  intermediate  between  these,  neither  between 
disease  and  health,  nor  between  the  odd  and  the  even.  Those 
contraries,  again,  have  something  intermediate,  in  which  one 
of  them  need  not  be  inherent,  as  black  and  white  are  naturally 
in  body,  but  it  is  not  necessary,  that  one  of  these,  should  be 
inherent  in  body,  for  every  body,  is  not  white  or  black. 
Vileness,  also  and  worth,  are  predicated  of  man,  and  of  many 
others,  yet  one  of  these,  need  not  be  in  those  things  of  which 
it  is  predicated,  for  not  all  things  are  either  vile  or  worthy  ; 
at  least,  there  is  something  intermediate,  as  between  white 
and  black,  there  is  dark  brown,  and  pale,  and  many  other 
colours,  but  between  vileness  and  worth,  that,  is  intermediate, 
which  is  neither  vile,  nor  worthy.  In  some  instances,  the  inter- 
mediates have  names,  thus,  the  dark  brown,  and  the  pale,  and 
such  colours  are  media  between  white  and  black,  but  in  other 
cases,  it  is  not  easy  to  assign  a  name  to  the  intermediate,  but  the 
latter  i3  defined,  by  the  negation  of  either  extreme,  as,  for  exam- 
ple, whatever  is  neither  good  nor  bad,  nor  just  nor  unjust.1 

Privation,  however,2  and  habit  are  predicated   3.  opposition 

'  Vide  Whately,  book  ii.  ch.  5,  sect.  1 ;  also  book  ii.  ch.  3,  sect.  4  ;  also 
Metaph.  lib.  iv.  c.  10. 
8  Cf.  Metaph.  lib.  iv.  c.  22  and  23.     Examples  of  Positive,  Privative, 

d  2 


36  aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  x. 

of  habit  and  of  something  identical,  as  sight  and  blindness  of  the 
privation.  eye^  an(j  universally,  in  whatever  the  habit  is  natu- 

rally adapted  to  be  produced,  of  such  is  either  predicated.  We 
say  then,  that  each  of  the  things  capable  of  receiving  habit  is 
deprived  of  it,  when  it  is  not  in  that,  wherein  it  might  naturally 
be,  and  when  it  is  adapted  naturally  to  possess  it ;  thus  we  say 
that  a  man  is  toothless,  not  because  he  has  no  teeth,  and  blind, 
not  because  he  has  no  sight,  but  because  he  has  them  not,  Avhec 
he  might  naturally  have  them,  for  some  persons  from  their  birth, 
have  neither  sight  nor  teeth,  yet  they  are  neither  called  tooth- 
i.  Distinction  less  nor  blind.  To  be  deprived  of,  and  to  possess 
in  the  meaning  habit,  then,  are  not  privation  and  habit,  for  the 

of  habitual  and       .,.,,.      ,  ,  .        ..         .      ,  ,.     -,  •    , 

privative  op-  sight  is  habit,  but  the  privation  is  blindness,  but 
position.  ^0  p0Ssess  sight  is  not  sight,  nor  to  be  blind,  blind- 

ness, for  blindness  is  a  certain  privation,  but  the  being  blind 
is  to  be  deprived,  and  is  not  privation,  for  if  blindness  were 
the  same  as  being  blind,  both  might  be  predicated  of  the  same 
person,  but  a  man  is  said  to  be  blind,  yet  he  is  never  called 
blindness.  To  be  deprived  also,  and  to  possess  habit,  appear 
to  be  similarly  opposed,  as  privation  and  habit,  since  the  mode 
of  opposition  is  the  same,  for  as  blindness  is  opposed  to  sight,  so 
likewise  is  the  being  blind,  opposed  to  the  possession  of  sight.1 
4.  opposition  Neither  is  that,  which  falls  under  affirmation  and 
of  affirmative  negation,  affirmation  and  negation  ;  for  affirmation 
is  an  affirmative  sentence,  and  negation  a  negative 

and  Negative  words  are  given  in  Hill's  Logic,  p.  27.  Aldrich's  definition 
of  the  three  will  be  remembered  here,  namely,  that  the  first  signifies  the 
presence  of  an  attribute ;  the  second,  its  absence  from  a  subject  capable 
of  it;  the  last,  its  absence  from  a  subject  incapable  of  it.  A  definite 
noun  and  its  corresponding  indefinite  noun  together,  constitute  a  perfect 
division. 

1  This  opposition  between  propositions  is  said  to  be  as  to  their  quality  ; 
to  this  may  be  appended  that  contrariety  of  quality  which  exists  between 
two  particulars,  properly  called  the  opposition  of  sub-contraries.  It  may 
here  be  observed,  that  though  this  last-named  form  of  contrariety  is  ad- 
mitted by  Aristotle,  (Int.  ch.  7,)  he  does  not  use  the  term  v-nevavrnoQ  as 
expressive  of  it,  but  calls  it,  in  Anal.  Prior,  ii.  1 5,  an  opposition  /card  tt)v 
\iZiv.  The  term  is  used  by  the  Greek  commentators,  (Ammonius  Schol. 
p.  115,  a.  15,)  Boethius  Int.  ad  Syll.  p.  564.  A  poetical  example  of  the 
mutual  subversion  of  some  relative  opposites  may  be  found  in  Shaks- 
peare's  King  John,  act  iii.  scene  1 : 

"  Indirection  thereby  grows  direct. 
And  falsehood  falsehood  cures  :  as  fire  cools  fire 
Within  the  scorched  veins  of  one  new  burn'd." 


CHAP.  X.]  THE    CATEGORIES.  37 

sentence,  but  nothing  which  falls  under  affirmation  and  nega- 
tion is  a  sentence  (but  a  thing).  Still  these  are  said  to  be 
mutually  opposed,  as  affirmation  and  negation,  since  in  them 
the  mode  of  opposition  is  the  same,  for  as  affirmation  is  some- 
times opposed  to  negation,  for  example,  "he  sits"  to  "he  does 
not  sit,"  so  that  thing  which  is  under  each  is  opposed,  as 
"  sitting  "  to  "  not  sitting." 

But  that  privation  and  habit,  are  not  opposed 
as  relatives,  is  evident,  since  what  a  thing  is,  is   and  habit  not 
not  asserted  of  its  opposite,  for  sight  is  not  the  relative]y  op- 
sight  of  blindness,  nor  in  any  other  way  spoken 
in  reference  to  it,  so  also  blindness,  cannot  be  called  the  blind- 
ness of  sight,  but  blindness  indeed  is  said  to  be  the  privation 
of  sight,  not  the  blindness  of  sight.     Moreover,  all  relatives 
are  referred  to  reciprocals,  so  that  if  blindness  were  relative, 
it  would  reciprocate  with  that  to  which  it  is  referred,  but  it 
does  not  reciprocate,  for  sight  is  not  said  to  be  the  sight  of 
jlindness. 

From  these  things,  also,  it  is  manifest  that  those  which  are 
predicated,  according  to  privation  and  habit,  are  not 
;ontrarily  opposed,  for  of  contraries  which  have  [rarity?*  C°" 
no  intermediate,  one  must  always  necessarily  be 
inherent,  wherein  it  is  naturally  adapted  to  be  inherent,  or  of 
which  it  is  predicated,  but  between  these,  there  is  no  inter- 
mediate thing  wherein  it  was  necessary  that  the  one  should  be  in 
what  was  capable  of  receiving  it,  as  in  the  case,  of  disease  and 
health,  in  odd  and  the  even  number.  Of  those  however  between 
which  there  is  an  intermediate,  it  is  never  necessary  that  one 
should  be  inherent  in  every  thing  ;  for  neither  is  it  necessary 
that  every  thing  capable  of  receiving  it,  should  be  white  or 
black,  or  hot  or  cold,  since  there  is  no  prevention  to  an  interme- 
diate being  between  them.  Again,  of  these  also  there  was  a  cer- 
tain medium,  of  which  it  was  not  requisite  that  one  should  be 
in  its  recipient,  unless  where  one  is  naturally  inherent,  as  in  fire 
to  be  hot,  and  in  snow  to  be  white  :  still  in  these,  one,  must 
of  necessity  be  definitely  inherent,  and  not  in  whatever  way 
it  may  happen,  for  neither  does  it  happen  that  fire  is  cold, 
nor  that  snow  is  black.1  Wherefore  it  is  not  necessary  that  one 
of  them  should  be  in  every  thing  capable  of  receiving  it,  but 

'  Vide  Whately  and  Hill's  Logic,  De  terminorum  distributione :  also 
the  former  upon  Fallacies,  book  i.  sections  1  and  13. 


38  Aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  x. 

only  in  those  wherein  the  one  is  naturally  inherent,  and  in 
these,  that  which  is  definitely  and  not  casually,  one.  In 
privation  however,  and  habit,  neither  of  the  above-men- 
tioned particulars  is  true,  since  it  is  not  always  necessary 
that  one  should  be  inherent  in  what  is  capable  of  receiv- 
ing it,  as  what  is  not  yet  naturally  adapted  to  have  sight, 
is  neither  said  to  be  blind  nor  to  have  si°rht ; 

6.  Nature  of 

intermediates  wherefore  these  things  will  not  be  of  such  contra- 
ct posTtion'0  r*es  as  nave  nothing  intermediate.  But  neither, 
on  the  other  hand,  will  they  be  amongst  those 
which  have  something  intermediate,  since  it  is  necessary  that 
at  some  time,  one  of  them,  should  be  inherent  in  every  thing  ca- 
pable of  receiving  it :  thus  when  a  man  is  naturally  fitted  to 
have  sight,  then  he  will  be  said  to  be  blind,  or  to  have  sight, 
and  one  of  these,  not  definitely,  but  whichever  may  happen, 
since  he  need  not  necessarily  be  blind,  nor  see,  but  either,  as  it 
may  happen.  In  respect  nevertheless  of  contraries,  which  have 
an  intermediate,  it  is  by  no  means  necessary  that  one,  should 
be  inherent  in  every  thing,  but  in  some  things,  and  in  these, 
one  of  them  definitely,  and  neither  casually,  so  that  things 
which  are  opposed  according  to  privation  and  habit,  are  evi- 
dently not  in  either  of  these  ways  opposed,  as  contraries. 

Again,  in  contraries,  when  the  recipient  exists,  a  change 
into  each  other  may  happen,  unless  one  is  naturally  inherent 
in  something,  as  for  instance,  in  fire  to  be  hot.  It  is  possible 
also  for  the  healthy  to  be  sick,  the  white  to  become  black, 
cold  to  become  hot,  (and  the  hot  to  become  cold)  ;  from  good 
it  is  possible  to  become  bad,  and  from  bad  good,  for  he 
who  is  depraved,  being  led  to  better  pursuits  and  discourses, 
advances,  though  but  a  little,  to  be  better,  and  if  he  once  makes 
an  advancement  ever  so  little,  he  will  evidently  become  either 
altogether  changed,  or  have  made  a  very  great  proficiency,1 

1  Vide  Ethics,  book  ii.  ch.  1 ;  <ilso  Magna  Moralia,  and  Metaph.  lib. 
viii.  It  will  be  observed  that  here,  as  elsewhere,  he  speaks  of  moral,  not 
intellectual  advancement:  Truth,  however,  he  considers  the  work  of 
both  the  intellectual  parts  of  the  soul.  Ethics,  book  vi.  ch.  2.  See  Mer- 
chant of  Venice,  act  iv.  scene  1 ;  and  Massinger's  beautiful  lines  on  the 
progress  of  moral  habit  in  the  5th  act,  2nd  scene,  of  the  Virgin  Martyr : 
also  the  duty  of  increasing  the  mental  powers,  Hamlet,  act  iv.  sc.  4 : 

"  Sure  he  that  made  us  with  such  large  disccurse, 

Looking  before  and  after,  gave  us  not 

That  capability  and  godlike  reason 

To  fas  In  us  unused." 


CHAP.  X.J  THE    CATEGORIES.  39 

since  he  ever  becomes  more  disposed  to  virtue,  even  if  he  has  ob- 
tained the  smallest,  increase,  from  the  beginning.  Wherefore 
he  will  probably  acquire  greater  increase,  and  this  perpetually 
occurring,  he  will  at  last  be  transformed  entirely  to  a  contrary 
habit,  unless  he  be  prevented  by  time  ;  but  in  privation  and 
habit,  it  is  impossible  for  a  mutual  change  to  occur,  since  it 
may  take  place  from  habit  to  privation,  but  from  privation  to 
habit  is  impossible,  as  neither  can  he  who  has  become  blind, 
again  see,  the  bald  again  have  hair,  nor  has  the  toothless  ever 
yet  again  got  teeth. 

Whatever  things  are  opposed,   as  affirmation   7  The      u 
and  negation,  are  evidently  opposed  according  to   Harity  of  affir- 

j?.-,         ,  ,.  ••  j  •  •      .,  mative, and  ne- 

none  or  the  above-mentioned  modes,  since  in  these   sative  opposi- 

alone  it  is  always  necessary  that  one  should  be   ti.on>  **' one 

*  *>  should  be  true 

true,  but  the  other  false ; l  as  neither,  is  it  al-  and  the  other 
ways  necessary  in  contraries  that  one  should  be  false' 
true  but  the  other  false,  nor  in  relatives,  nor  in  habit  and 
privation.  For  instance,  health  and  disease,  are  contrary,  yet 
neither  of  them  is  either  true  or  false ;  so  also  the  double  and 
the  half  are  relatively  opposed,  and  neither  of  them  is  either 
true  or  false ;  nor  in  things  which  are  predicated  as  to  priva- 
tion and  habit,  as  sight  and  blindness.  In  short,  nothing  pre- 
dicated without  any  conjunction,  is  either  true  or  false,  and 
all  the  above-named  are  predicated  without  conjunction.  Not 
but  that  a  thing  of  this  kind  may  appear,  to  happen  in  contraries, 
which  are  predicated  conjunctively,  for  "  Socrates  is  well"  is 
opposed  to  "  Socrates  is  sick,"  2  yet  neither  in  these  is  it  always 
necessary,  that  one  should  be  true  and  the  other  false,  for 
while  Socrates  lives,  one  will  be  true  and  the  other  false,  but 
when  he  is  not  alive,  both  will  be  false,  since  neither  is  it 
true  that  Socrates  is  sick,  nor  that  he  is  well,  when  he  is  not 

1  Vide  rules  of  natural  opposition  in  the  common  Logical  Treatises. 

2  These  are  properly  contradictories,  one  being  true  and  the  other  false, 
but  the  definition  of  contradictories  does  not  include  them  as  being  given 
by  Aldrich  only  of  universals ;  the  definition  however  given  in  Anal. 
Post,  i.  2,  6,  will  include  them — avrityaoiQ  Si  avriQtaiq  ?)c  oi>k  sort 
fi(ra£,v  Kaff  avTt]\'.  Some  logicians  call  the  opposition  of  singulars 
secondary  contradiction.  Boethius,  p.  613,  regards  such  instances  as  con- 
tradictories ;  also  Wallis,  lib.  ii.  ch.  5.  Compare  Aldrich's  Logic  upon 
rules  of  contradiction  :  it  is  remarkable  that  he  does  not  mention  the  op- 
position of  singulars  until  he  comes  to  the  causes  of  opposition  of  propo- 
sitions.    Cf.  Interpretation  7,  Anal.  Prior,  xi.  15. 


40  Aristotle's  organon.  |  chap,  xi 

in  existence  at  all.  In  privation  and  habit,  then  when  the  sub- 
ject is  non-existent,  neither  is  true,  but  when  the  subject  exists, 
the  one  is  not  always  true,  nor  the  other  false.  "  Socrates 
sees  "  is  opposed  to  "  Socrates  is  blind,"  as  privation  and  habit, 
and  whilst  he  exists,  one  need  not  be  true  or  false,  for  when  he 
is  not  naturally  fitted  to  possess  them,  both  are  false,  but  when 
Socrates  does  not  exist  at  all,  both  will  thus  be  false,  that  he 
sees,  and  that  he  is  blind.  In  affirmation  and  negation  always, 
if  Socrates  be  or  be  not,  one  will  always  be  false  and  the  other 
true  ;  for  it  is  evident  with  respect  to  these  two,  "  Socrates  is 
sick,"  and  "  Socrates  is  not  sick,"  that  when  he  exists  one  of 
them  is  true  and  the  other  false  ;  and  in  like  manner  when  he 
does  not  exist,  for  in  the  latter  case  that  he  is  ill  is  false,  but 
that  he  is  not  ill  is  true ;  so  that  in  those  things  alone  which 
are  affirmatively  and  negatively  opposed  will  it  be  the  pecu- 
liarity that  one  of  them  is  either  true  or  false. 

Chap.    XL — Opposites  continued,  especially  as  to  the  contrariety  be- 
tween the  Evil  and  the  Good. 

1.  Opposition  "  Evil  "  is  of  necessity  opposed  to  good,  and 
of  good  and       this  is  evident  from  an  induction  of  singulars, 

as  disease  to  health,  and  cowardice  to  courage, 
and  similarly  of  the  rest.  But  to  evil,  at  one  time,  good,  is 
contrary,  and  at  another,  evil,  for  to  indigence  being  an  evil, 
Rhet.  b  i.  c.  7  excess  *s  contrary,  which  is  also  an  evil ;  in  like 
and  Eth.  t>.  n.    manner,  mediocrity,  which  is  a  good,  is  opposed  to 

each  of  them.  A  man  may  perceive  this  in  re- 
spect of  a  few  instances,  but  in  the  majority  the  contrary  to 
evil  is  always  good.1 

Again,  of  contraries  it  is  not  required,  if  one  is, 
contrary6exists    that  the  remainder  should  be;  for  when  every 

1  Compare  note  in  the  preceding  chapter  relative  to  the  observation  of 
Archytas  as  to  generic  and  specific  contrariety,  whence  it  will  be  seen 
that  this  chapter  is  nothing  else  than  an  elaboration  of  the  principle  he 
lays  down.  He  adds  in  his  treatise  on  Opposites,  "  There  are  three  dif- 
ferences of  contraries ;  for  some  things  are  opposed  as  good  to  evil,  as  for 
instance  health  to  sickness,  some  as  evil  to  evil,  as  avarice  to  prodigality, 
and  some  as  neither  to  neither,  as  the  white  to  the  black,  and  the  heavy 
to  the  light."  What  he  calls  "  neither,"  and  Aristotle  "  the  negation  of 
extremes,"  subsequent  philosophers  called  "  indifferent,"  adtaQopa. 
Comp.  Cic.  ad  Atticum,  also  Sanct.  Chrys.  in  Ep.  ad  Ephes.  c.  5. 


CHAP.  XII. J 


THE   CATEGORIES. 


41 


man  is  well,  there  will  indeed  be  health,  and  not   it  is  not  neces- 
disease,  and  so  also  when  all  things  are  white,  there   other 'shouw 
will  be  whiteness,  but  not  blackness.     Besides,  if  exist— but 
*  Socrates  is  well"  be  the  contrary  of  "  Socrates  is   destroys  the 
ill,"  and  both  cannot  possibly  be  inherent  in  the   other- 
same  subject,  it  follows,  that  when  one  of  the  contraries  exists^ 
the  other  cannot  possibly  exist,  for  "  Socrates  is  well "  exist- 
ing, "  Socrates  is  ill"  cannot  exist.1 

Contraries,  however,  evidently  are,  by  their  na- 
ture, adapted  to  subsist  about  the  same  thing,   genwan^nhe- 
either  in  species  or  genus,  since  disease  and  health   rent  in  similar 
naturally  subsist  in  the  body  of  an  animal,  but   cTensera  °r  spe" 
whiteness  and  blackness  simply  in  body,  and  jus- 
tice and  injustice  in  the  soul  of  man. 

Notwithstanding,  it  is  requisite  that  all  contraries  be  either 
in  the  same  genus,  or  in  contrary  genera,  or  be  ge- 
nera themselves ;  for  white  and  black  are  in  the 
same  genus,  as  "  colour  '*  is  the  genus  of  them  ; 
but  justice  and  injustice  in  contrary  genera,  for 
"virtue"  is  the  genus  of  one,  but  "vice  "  of  the 
other  ;  lastly,  "good"  and  "bad "are  not  in  a  genus, 
but  are  themselves  the  genera  of  certain  things. 


4.  They  must 
be  either  in  the 
same  genus,  or 
in  contrary  ge- 
nera, or  be  ge- 
nera them- 
selves. 


Cha p.  XII.-—  Of  Priority? 

A  thing  is  said  to  be  prior  to  another  in  four 
respects :  first  and  most  properly,  in  respect  of  fourfold!  y 
time,  according  to  which,  one  is  said  to  be  older   1st.  in  respect 

• — f  •  i  i  ■  •      •  n    i     of  time. 

and  more  ancient  than  another,  since  it  is  called 

older  and  more  ancient,  because  the  time  is  longer.     Next, 

when  it  does  not  reciprocate,  according  to  the   „  ,  __ 

.  L  .  .  °  2nd,  When 

consequence  ot  existence  :  thus  one  is  prior  to  two,  there  is  no  re- 
for  two  existing,  it  follows  directly  that  one  ex-  ^^^  t0 
ists  ;  but  when  one  is,  it  is  not  necessary  that  two  quence  of  ex- 
should  be,  hence  the  consequence  of  the  re- 
mainder's existence  does  not  reciprocate  from  the  existence  of 
the  one ;  but  such  a  thing  appears  to  be  prior,  from  which 
the  consequence  of  existence  does  not  reciprocate. 

1  Logic  taking  no  cognizance  of  understood  matter,  the  necessary,  im- 
possible, and  contingent  should  be  omitted  from  the  table  of  opposition.— 
Mansel.     Compare  also  Whately  de  Oppositione,  cited  above. 

a  Cf.  Metaph.  lib.  iv.  c.  11. 


42  ARISTOTLE'S    ORGANON.  [CHAP.  Xn. 

3rd,  in  respect  Thirdly,  the  prior  is  that  predicated  according 
of  order.  to  a  certam  order,  as  in  the  instance  of  sciences  and 

discourses,  for  in  demonstrative  sciences,  the  prior  and  the 
posterior,  subsist  in  order,  since  the  elements  are  prior  in 
order,  to  the  diagrams,  and  in  grammar,  letters  are  before 
syllables  ;  so  also  of  discourses,  as  the  proem  is  prior,  in  order, 
to  the  narration. 

Moreover,  besides  what  we  have  mentioned,  the 
kn '• In  eXCel"  better  and  more  excellent  appear  to  be  prior  by 
nature.  The  common  people  are  accustomed  to 
say,  that  those  whom  they  chiefly  honour  and  especially  re- 
gard, are  prior  in  their  esteem;1  but  this  is  nearly  the  most 
foreign  of  all  the  modes,  wherefore  such  are  (nearly)  the  modes 
of  priority  which  have  been  enumerated. 
2   Another  Besides  the   above-mentioned,   there  may  yet 

mode  of  prior-  appear  to  be  another  mode  of  the  prior ;  as  of 
edy,"vhereeone  things  reciprocating,  according  to  the  consequence 
thing  is  the       0f  existence,  that  which  in  any  respect  is  the  cause 

CiillSt'  01  3.11- 

other's  exist-  of  the  existence  of  the  one,  may  justly  be  said  to  be 
ing-  by  nature  prior,  and  that  there  are,  certain  things 

of  this  kind,  is  manifest.  For  that  man  exists,  reciprocates, 
according  to  the  consequence  of  existence,  with  the  true  sen- 
tence respecting  him,  since  if  man  is,  the  sentence  is  true,  by 
which  we  say,  that  man  is,  and  it  reciprocates,  since  if  the 
sentence  be  true,  by  which  we  say  that  man  is,  then  man  is. 
Notwithstanding,  a  true  sentence,  is  by  no  means  the  cause  of 
a  thing's  existence,  but  in  some  way,  the  thing  appears  the 
cause  of  the  sentence  being  true,  for  in  consequence  of  a  thing 
existing,  or  not  existing:,  is  a  sentence  said  to  be  true  or 
false.  Wherefore  one  thing  may  be  called  prior  to  another, 
according  to  five  modes.2 

1  In  the  text,  rovg  Evrifiwrepovg.  The  adverbial  construction  repre- 
sented in  Greek  by  the  neuter  plural,  was  frequently  the  form  of  employ- 
ing -n-pwToc  in  this  sense  :  thus  Herod,  vi.  100,  Ato-%(V»/£  6  NoOwi'oe  iwv 
twv  'Epsrpiewv  rd  npiora.  In  Latin  the  same  expression  occurs  for 
great  men,  primates  equivalent  to  optimates,  and  sometimes  primores ; 
thus  Liv.  Primoribus  patrum ;  Hor.  Populi  primores,  etc.  An  odd  in- 
stance of  "first"  for  "noblest"  occurs  in  Coriolanus,  act  iv.  scene  1, 

"  My  first  son, 
Whither  wilt  thou  go  ?"  where  see  note,  Knight's  ed. 

2  The  tautological  baldness  of  this  whole  chapter,  it  is  hopeless  to 
remedy,  its  arrangement  also  is  slovenly :  for  the  latter  portion,  the  next 


CHAP.  XIII.]  THE    CATEGORIES.        ■  43 


Chap.  XIII. — Of  things  simultaneous. 

Things  are  called  simultaneous  simply  and  most   ,  Those  thi 
properly,  whose  generation  occurs  at  the  same   are  simuitane- 

•  ous  which  at 

time,   for  neither  is   prior   or  posterior ;    these,   the  same  time 
therefore,  are  said  to  be  simultaneous  as  to  time.   are  produced, 

'  .  and  which  re- 

mit by  nature  those  are  simultaneous,  which  re-   ciprocate,  but 

ciprocate  according  to  the  consequence  of  exist-   cause'the*1" 

ence,  although  one,  is  by  no  means  the  cause  of  other's  exist- 

the  existence  of  the  other,  as  in  the  double  and 

the  half,  for  these  reciprocate ;  thus  the  double  existing,  the 

half  also  exists,  and  the  half  existing,  the  double  exists,  but 

neither  is  the  cause  of  existence  to  the  other. 

Those,  also,  which  being  derived  from  the  same   „   _ 

'.,...  b      ,-,  ,  .  ,     2.  Or  which  as 

genus,  are  by  division  mutually  opposed,  are  said  species  of  the 
to  be  naturally  simultaneous  ; '  but  they,  are  said  l^slTin'the 
to  have  a  division  opposite  to  each  other,  which  same  relation 
subsist  according  to  the  same  division  ;  thus  the 
winged  is  opposed  to  pedestrian  and  aquatic,  as  these  being 
derived  from  the  same  genus,  are  by  division  mutually  opposed, 
for  animal  is  divided  into  these,  viz.  into  the  winged,  the  pe- 
destrian, and  aquatic,  and  none  of  these  is  prior  or  posterior, 
but  things  of  this  kind  appear  naturally  simultaneous.  Each 
of  these  again,  may  be  divided  into  species,  for  instance,  the 
winged,  the  pedestrian,  and  the  aquatic  ;  wherefore,  those  will 
be  naturally  simultaneous  which,  derived  from  the  same  genus, 
subsist  according  to  the  same  division.  But  genera  are  al- 
ways prior  to  species,  since  they  do  not  reciprocate  according 
to  the  consequence  of  existence  ;2  for  the  aquatic  existing,  ani- 
mal exists,  but  though  animal  exists,  it  is  not  necessary  that 
the  aquatic  should. 

Hence  those  are  called  naturally  simultaneous,  which  in- 
deed reciprocate,  according  to  the  consequence  of  existence ; 
but  the  one  is  by  no  means  the  cause  of  existence  to  the  other, 
which  is  also  the  case  with  things  that,  derived  from  the  same 

chapter  will  appear  elucidatory,  and,  in  fact,  is  the  same  statement  of  the 
whole,  in  reverse. 

1  Porphyry  recognises  only  a  relative  difference  between  two  given 
species.     See  Introduction ;  also  Hill's  Logic. 

2  See  Whately,  book  ii.  ch.  5. 


44  aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  xiv. 

genus,  have  by  division  a  mutual  opposition ;  those,  how- 
ever, are  simply  simultaneous  whose  generation  is  at  the  same 
time.1 

i  Chap.  XIV.— Of  Motion? 

i.  Motion  of  Of  motion,  there  are  six  species,  generation,  cor- 
six  kmds.  ruption,    increase,    diminution,    alteration,    and 

change  of  place. 

The  other  motions  then  evidently  differ  from  each  other, 
for  neither  is  generation,  corruption,  nor  increase,  diminu- 
tion, nor  alteration,  change  of  place,  and  so  of  the  rest.  In 
2.  Alteration  the  case  of  alteration  however,  there  is  some 
reiItiventobthe  doubt,  wnether  it  be  not  sometimes  necessary  that 
rest,  this  dis-  what  is  altered,  be  so,  in  respect  to  some  one,  of 
proved.  tjie  other  motions,  but  this  is  not  true,  for  it  hap- 

pens that  we  are  altered,  as  to  nearly  all  the  passions,  or  at 
least  the  greater  part  of  them,  without  any  participation 
of  the  other  motions,  for  it  is  not  necessary  that  what  is 
passively  moved  should  be  either  increased  or  diminished. 
Wherefore,  alteration  will  differ  from  the  other  motions,  since 
1st,  By  no  in-     if  it  were  the  same,  it  would  be  necessary  that 

nutlon  n'ecJs"""  wnat  is  altered>  be  forthwith  increased  or  dimin- 
sariiy  occurring  ished,  or  follow  some  of  the  other  motions,  but 
tered!at  ls  al"  this  is  not  necessary.  Similarly,  also,  what  is  in- 
2nd,  By  no        creased  or  moved  with  any  other  motion,  ought 

change  taking      ,.  .,         ,,.  ..,    N    J ,  ,.'        ° 

place  in  to  be  altered  (in  quality) ;  but  some  things  are 

quality.  increased  which  are  not  so  altered,  as  a  square 

is  increased  when  a  gnomon3  is  placed  about  it,  but  it  has 

1  The  office  of  Logic  being  to  guard  against  ambiguity  in  the  use  of 
terms;  it  is  clear  that  by  nominal  division  alone,  species  from  the  same 
genus  will  often  have  a  subordinate  opposition,  as  antagonistic  in  its  na- 
ture, as  opposite  genera ;  for  example,  purple,  yellow,  etc.,  under  colour. 
Boethius  uses  division  in  three  senses :  1.  Of  a  genus  into  species.  2.  Of 
a  whole  into  its  parts.  3.  Of  an  equivocal  term  into  its  several  significa- 
tions. Cicero,  Top.  vi.  ch.,  calls  the  first,  divisio,  the  second,  partitio. 
Aristotle  approves  division  by  contraries.  See  Top.  vi.  6,  3,  de  part. 
Anim.  i.  3. 

2  Compare  the  Physics,  books  iii.  v.  vi.  vii.  viii.,  also  Metaph.  lib.  x. 
ch.  9,  11,  12.  ^  In  the  11th  ch.  of  the  10th  book,  Meta.,  he  defines  motion, 
H  icivrjoig  tvepyua  fikv  tlvat  Soicti  rtc  are\?)g  SL  Vide  also  the  Scholia 
Marc.  ed.  Waitz,  'H  Kivqoig  kanv  l^dWa^ig  icai  tKcrracrig. 

3  The  following  figure  will  illustrate  this  comparison :  the  use  of  the 
yvwfiov  being  the  ascertainment  of  right  angles. 


oriAP.  xv.] 


THE    CATEGORIES. 


3.  Generic  and 
specific  contra- 
riety to  motion. 


not  become  altered  (in  quality)  ;  and  in  like  manner  with  other 
things  of  this  kind,  so  that  these  motions  will  differ  from 
each  other. 

Nevertheless  simply,  rest  is  contrary  to  motion, 
the  several  rests  to  the  several  motions,  corrup- 
tion to  generation,  diminution  to  increase,  rest 
in  place  to  change  in  place ;  but  change  to  a  contrary  place 
seems  especially  opposed,  as  ascent  to  descent,  downwards  to 
upwards.  Still  it  is  not  easy,  to  define  the  contrary  to  the  re- 
mainder of  these  specified  motions,  but  it  seems  to  have  no 
contrary,  unless  some  one  should  oppose  to  this,  rest  according 
to  quality,  or  change  of  quality  into  its  contrary,  just  as  in 
change  of  place,  rest  according  to  place,  or  change  to  a  contrary 
place.  For  alteration  is  the  mutation  of  quality,  so  that  to  mo- 
tion according  to  quality,  will  rest  according  to  quality,  or 
change  to  the  contrary  of  the  quality,  be  opposed  ;  thus  becoming 
white  is  opposed  to  becoming  black,  since  a  change  in  quality 
occurs,  there  being  an  alteration  of  quality  into  contraries. 


Chap.  XV.—  Of  the  verb  «  to  Haver 

To  have,  is  predicated  in  many  modes ;  either 
as  habit  and  disposition  or  some  other  quality, 
for  we  are  said  to  have  knowledge  and  virtue ; l 


3              \ 

\ 

1st           / 

/    Square 

/ 

a          / 

s           m 
/ 

1 

O            N. 

\ 

I.  Having  pre- 
dicated in 
many  ways. 
1.  Quality.      1 


1  This  form  is  often  cognate,  and  almost  identical  with  the  7th,  of  pos- 
session, thus  St.  Paul's  Ep.  2  Cor.  iv.  7 ;  as  to  the  2nd,  the  idiom  of  the 
English  does  not  fully  correspond  with  the  Greek  Ixuv,  our  word  in  re- 
lation to  quantity  being  "  to  hold."  A  rare  use  of  the  word  "havings  " 
occurs  in  the  Lover's  Complaint  of  Shakspeare  ;  see  Knight's  edition  : 
"  Whose  rarest  havings  made  the  blossoms  dote." 


46  Aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  i. 

2.  Quantity  or  as  to  quantity,  as  the  size  which  any  one  has  ; 
thus  he  is  said  to  have  the  size  of  three  or  four  cubits  ;  or 

3.  investiture,    as  things   about  the   body,  as  a  garment  or    a 

4.  in  a  part.      tunic  ; '  or  as  in  a  part,  as  a  ring  in  the  hand  ; 

5.  As  to  a  part,   or  as  a  part,  as  the  hand  or  the  foot ;  or  as  in  a 

6.  in  measure,  vessel,  as  a  bushel  has  wheat,  or  a  flagon,  wine, 
for  the  flagon  is  said  to  have2  the  wine,  and  the  bushel  the 
wheat ;  all  these  therefore  are  said  to  have,  as  in  a  vessel  ;  or 

as  a  possession,  for  we  are  said  to  have  a  house  or 

7.  Possession.      ,        -1 

land. 
A  man  is  also  said  to  have  a  wife,  and  the  wife  a  husband, 
but  the  mode  now  mentioned,  of  "  to  have,"  seems  the  most 
8  Also  indi-  foreign,  for  we  mean  nothing  else  by  having  a  wife, 
rectiy  or  by  than  that  she  cohabits  with  a  man  ;  there  may 
analogy.  perhaps  appear  to  be  some  other  modes  of  having, 

but  those  usually  mentioned  have  nearly  all  been  enumerated. 


ON  INTERPRETATION.3 

Chap.  I. — What  Interpretation  is,  which  is  here  discussed:  of  the 
Symbols  or  Exponents  of  the  Passions  by  the  voice — of  Nouns  and 
Verbs. 

l. Things  enun-  We  must  first  determine  what  a  noun,  and  what 

cia.ted  h? the  a  verb,  are  ;  next,  what  are  negation,  affirmation, 

bois  of  the  pas-  enunciation,  and  a  sentence, 
sions  in  the  Those  things  therefore  which  are  in  the  voice, 

1  This  is  Shakspearian  usage  also.  Sometimes  this  form  is  applied 
generally  to  condition  or  estate,  and  even  attire,  and  manner.  See  Win- 
ter's Tale,  iv.  3.     The  next  are  in  the  sense  of  "  holding,"  again. 

3  More  properly  \wpeTv.  It  is  evident  throughout  this  chapter,  that 
the  elliptical  modes  in  which  we  employ  "  have  "  as  an  auxiliary  verb 
are  endless,  and  in  the  use  of  it,  the  assimilation  of  the  English  to  the 
Greek  is  peculiar.  Sometimes  a  very  decided  verb  is  omitted,  and  the 
auxiliary  made  to  stand  alone;  thus,  in  K.  Henry  VIII.  act  ii.  sc.  2, 

"All  the  clerks, 

I  mean  the  learned  ones,  in  Christian  kingdoms, 

Have  their  free  voices  " for  "  have  sent "  their  free  voices. 

For  the  Aristotelian  usages  of  the  word,  compare  Metaph.  lib.  iv.  c.  23. 

3  Having  discussed  in  the  Categories  the  doctrine  of  simple  terms, 
Aristotle,  in  the  following  treatise,  proceeds  to  the  discussion  of  Proposi- 


CHAP.  1.1  ON    INTERPRETATION.  47 

are  symbols  of  the  passions  of  the  soul,  and  when  written,  are 
symbols  of  the  (passions)  in  the  voice,  and  as  there  are  not  the 
same  letters  among  all  men,  so  neither  have  all  the  same  voices, 
yet  those  passions  of  the  soul,  of  which  these  are  primarily  the 
signs,  are  the  same  among  all,  the  things  also,  of  which  these 
are  the  similitudes,  are  the  same.  About  these  latter,  we  have 
spoken  in  the  treatise  "  Of  the  Soul," '  for  they  are  parts  be- 
longing to  another  discussion,  but  as  in  the  soul,  there  is 
sometimes  a  conception,  without  truth  or  falsehood,  and  at 
another  time,  it  is  such,  as  necessarily  to  have  one  of  these, 
inherent  in  it,  so  also  is  it  with  the  voice,  for  false-  2  Truth  and 
hood  and  truth  are  involved  in  composition  and  falsehood  of 
division.2     Nouns  therefone  and  verbs  of  them-   dependent  on 

tion,  which,  is  the  result  of  the  conjunction  of  simple  terms,  and  discard- 
ing the  other  species  of  sentence,  confines  himself  to  the  categoric  form 
of  the  enunciative  sentence  simply,  preparatory  to  the  systematic  inquiry 
into  the  nature  of  syllogism,  hereafter  to  be  conducted  in  the  Analytics. 
Indeed,  for  this  reason,  as  occupying  a  middle  place  between  simple  terms 
and  syllogism,  this  treatise  is  more  properly  introduced  here,  as  Waitz, 
Buhle,  Averrois,  and  Taylor  place  it,  than  after  the  Topics,  as  by  Bekker. 
So  highly  is  it  esteemed  by  Ammonius,  (in  librum  Aris.  de  Int.,  Vend. 
1545,)  that  he  states  his  gratitude  to  the  god  Hermes  if  he  shall  be  able 
to  add  any  thing  to  its  elucidation,  from  what  he  recollects  of  the  interpret- 
ations of  Proclus,  the  Platonist,  his  preceptor. 

As  to  the  title,  notwithstanding  much  difference  of  opinion,  the  fruit  of 
primary  misconception  of  the  term  (7rfp<  tpurjvtiag),  its  application  here 
seems  well  grounded,  as  descriptive  of  language  in  its  construction,  being 
enunciative  of  the  gnostic  powers  of  the  soul ;  it  may  therefore,  we 
think,  (with  the  learned  author  of  the  Prolegomena  Logica,  Mansel,)  be 
adequately  Anglicized,  "  Of  language  as  the  interpretation  of  thought." 
Boethe  defines  it,  "  Interpretatio  est  vox  significativa,  per  se  ipsam,  aliquid 
significans,"  to  which  Waitz  adds  the  remark,  "  latius  patet  tpfirjvtia 
quam  XtSic."  Isidore  of  Seville  observes  :  "  Omnis  elocutio  concept® 
rei  interpres  est :  inde  perihermeniam  nominant  quam  interpretationem 
nos  appellamus."  For  various  interpretations  of  the  word,  see  St.  Hilaire, 
de  la  Logique  d'  Aristote,  p.  i.  ch.  1(3.  The  treatise  itself  may  be  divided 
into  four  parts  :  First,  concerning  the  principles  of  the  enunciative  sen- 
tence, including  definitions  of  its  component  parts  ;  the  three  othera  in- 
forming us  of  proposition  :  as,  1st,  purely  enunciative ;  2nd,  more  complex, 
wherein  something  is  added  to  the  predicate,  making  in  fact  a  fourth 
term  ;  3rd,  modal :  at  the  end  he  annexes  an  inquiry  connected  with  a  case 
of  problematic  contrariety. 

1  Vide  de  Anim.  iii.  6  ;  also  Metaph. 

2  This  is  evident,  since  logic  itself  is  psychological;  but  observe,  he 
does  not  say  all  truth  is  conversant  with  composition  and  division,  the  last 
is  indeed  excluded  from  the  idealities  of  Plato.  Thought,  per  se,  has  no 
need  of  systematic  language,  the  most  accurate  development  of  which  does 


48  atcistotle's  organon.  [chap  n. 

composition  selves  resemble  conception,  without  composition 
wodrdds!Vlsi0symf  and  division,  as  "man,"  or  "white,"  when  some- 
bois.  '  thing  is  not  added,  for  as  yet  it  is  neither  true  nor 

false,  an  instance  of  which  is  that  the  w6rd  rpayiXacpoc1  sig- 
nifies something  indeed,  but  not  yet  any  thing  true  or  false, 
unless  to  be,  or  not  to  be,  is  added,  either  simply,  or  according 
to  time. 

Chap.  II. — Of  the  Noun  and  its  Case. 

1  Definition  ^  noun  therefore  is  a  sound  significant  2  by 
of  the  noun—  compact  without  time,  of  which  no  part  is  separ- 
ately signi-"  ately  significant ;  thus  in  the  noun  KdWnnrog,  the 
ficant— distinc-  '[n7r0Q  signifies  nothing  by  itself,  as  it  does  in  the 

tion  between  ° 

simple  and  sentence  koXoq  'Ltttvoq  ;  neither  does  it  happen  with 
composite.  simple  nouns  as  it  does  with  composite,  for  in  tbe 
former  there  is  by  no  means  the  part  significant,  but  in  the 
latter  a  part  would  be,  yet  signifies  nothing  separately,  as  in 
the  word  iwaKvpoKeXric,  3  the   KeXng  signifies  no- 

conffcflf*11*0'   tninS  ty  itself>-     But  il  is  according  to  compact,4 
because  naturally  there  is  no  noun  ;  but  when  it 

not  touch,  in  all  cases,  its  subtlety.  On  the  distinction  between  cn]/xt1ov 
and  6fj.oiw[xa,  see  Waitz,  vol.  i.  324.  It  will  be  remembered  that  the  legi- 
timate office  of  logic  is  not  establishment  of  the  truth  or  falsehood  of  the 
subject  matter,  except  in  so  far  as  that  truth  or  falsehood  results  from 
certain  relations  of  original  data  according  to  fixed  rules.  (Vide  Whately , 
Hill,  Huyshe.)  It  is  needless  to  quote  the  definition  given  by  Aldrich  of 
Proposition  here. 

1  That  is,  an  animal  partly  a  goat  and  partly  a  stag.  Compare  with 
this  and  the  following  chapters,  ch.  xx.  of  the  Poetics. 

2  <boj)>rj  <ji)ixavriKr),  called  by  Aldrich  vox,  by  Boethius  and  Petrus 
Hispanus,  vox,  signiticativa  ad  placitum.  Logical  nouns  are  equivalent 
to  simple  terms,  or  categorems,  in  opposition  to  syncategorems,  which  are 
not,  per  se,  significative.  Here  Aristotle  mentions  the  noun  and  the  verb  : 
Dut  (ch.  xx.  Poetics)  he  elsewhere  adds  the  conjunction  and  article 
((pwvai  aaiifioi).  Cf.   Harris  Hermes,  ch.  iii. ;    also  Hill's  Logic* 

3  A  piratical  ship.  The  word  is  a  vox  complexa — <pwv>),  avfiTmrXtyfikvi}, 
a  compound  word,  whereof  each  part  has  a  meaning  in  composition, 
001)'?}  aTrXij,  where  the  parts  have  no  meaning.  Vide  Sanderson's  Logic. 

4  Primo  quidem  declarat  conceptum  deinde  supponit  pro  re.  Aldrich. 
When  Aristotle  makes  the  assertion  in  the  text,  he  does  not  dissent  from  that 
of  Socrates  in  the  Cratylus ;  but  whilst  he  denies  the  subsistence  of  names 
from  nature,  an  opinion  adopted  by  Heraclitus,  he  shows  in  his  Physical 
Auscultation,  and  various  other  places,  that  names  accord  with  things.  In 
this  very  treatise  the  name  of  "  an  indefinite  noun,"  or  of  "  contradic- 


CnAP.  III.]  ON    INTERPRETATION.  49 

becomes  a  symbol,  since  illiterate  sounds  also  signify  some- 
thing, as  the  sounds  of  beasts,  of  which  there  is  no  noun. 

"  Not  man,"  however,  is  not  a  noun,  neither  is  a 
name  instituted  by  which  we  ought  to  call  it,  since    n'itJnot'anoun 
it  is  neither  a  sentence,  nor  a  negation ; '  but  let 
it  be  an  indefinite  noun  because  it  exists  in  respect  of  every 
thing  alike,  both  of  that  which  is,  and  of  that  which  is  not.2 
(friXwrog  indeed,  or  <bi\u>vi,   and  such  like  words    .  _ 

i  4.  Chscs  of  tne 

are  not  nouns,  but  cases  of  a  noun,3  but  the  de-   noun  differ 
finition  of  it  (that  is,  of  the  case)  is  the  same  as   {^Sajbein™ 
to  other  things  (with  the  definition  of  a  noun),  but   joined  to  the 
(it  differs  in)  that,  with  (the  verb)  "is"  or  "was"   they'slgnily1  a' 
or  "  will  be,"  it  does  not  signify  what  is  true  or   neither  truth 

n  ,  ,  ,  ,         °      /.       .„  i  ■   \  nor  falsehood. 

false,   but   the   noun   always    (signifies   this),  as 

"  Philonus  is,"  or  "  is  not,"  for  as  yet,  this  neither  signifies 

what  is  true,  nor  what  is  false. 

Chap.  III. —  Of  the  Verb,  its  Case,  and  of  those  called  Verbs 

generally* 

A  verb,  is  that  which,  besides  something  else,  sig-  1  Definjti0n 
nifies  time  ;  of  which  no  part  is  separately  signifi-  of  the  verb  or 
cant,  and  it  is  always  indicative  of  those  things  which  pw°' 

tion,"  given  by  him,  clearly  shows  his  opinion  about  names.  The  suppo- 
sitio  of  Aldrich  is  not  found  in  Aristotle,  but  may  be  traced  to  the  Greek 
Logic  of  Michael  Psellus. 

1  Not  a  noun,  that  is,  not  a  true  and  perfect  noun,  nor  a  sentence,  since 
it  is  neither  "  verum  vel  falsum  significans;"  neither  is  it  a  negation,  for  it 
wants  a  verb,  without  which  there  is  no  negation. 

2  Signifies  as  well  being  as  non-being :  in  the  original  bfioiiog  t<p' 
utovovv  virdpxt1-  Waitz  omits  the  rest  of  this  sentence  from  "indefi- 
nite noun." 

3  Aristotle  considers  the  oblique  cases  of  a  noun  (tttojchiq),  not  the  nomi- 
native, the  Stoics  regarded  the  nominative  (IvOtia)  also  a  case.  Oblique 
cases  are  syncategorematic,  that  is,  can  only  form  part  of  a  term,  the 
nominative  may  be  a  term  by  itself. 

4  Aristotle  does  not  employ  the  term  categorematic,  but  defines  his 
simple  terms,  opot  ilg  oi)e  SiaXitrai  r)  Ttporaaig, — with  him  categorema- 
tic words  are  the  noun  as  subject,  and  the  verb  as  predicate.  Vide  Boeth 
Introd.  ad  Syll.  and  Pet.  Hisp.  Tract  i.  Cf.  Trendelenburg,  Elementa,  §  3. 
Waitz,  vol.  i.  267.  The  copula  has  been  called  the  only  logical  verb,  but 
is,  properly  speaking,  no  verb  at  all,  and  cannot  correspond  with  the  pi\fia 
\,i  Aristotle,  except  by  coalescing  with  the  predicate.      Vide  Mansel's 


50  ARISTOTLE'S   ORGANON.  [CHAP.  m. 

are  asserted  of  something  else.  But  I  say  that  it  signifies 
time,  besides  something  else,  as  for  instance,  "health"  is  a 
noun,  but  "is  well"  is  a  verb  ;  for  it  signifies,  besides  being 
well,  that  such  is  the  case  now :  it  is  always  also  significant 
of  tilings  asserted  of  something  else,  as  of  those  which  are 
predicated  of  a  subject,  or  which  are  in  a  subject. 

Nevertheless  I  do  not  call,  "is  not  well,"  and,  "is 
ed  withMga""  not iU "  — ver bs  5  for  incleed they  signify  time,  be- 
tion,  or  in  its  sides  something  else,  and  are  always  (significant)  of 
theSpresent°,  is  something,  yet  a  name  is  not  given  to  this  difference, 
not  a  proper      jet  either  be  therefore  an  indefinite  verb,  because 

it  is  similarly  inherent  both  in  whatever  does,  and 
does  not  exist.1  So  also  "was  well"  or  "will  be  well"  are 
not  verbs,  but  they  are  cases  of  a  verb,  and  differ  from  a  verb, 
because  the  latter,  besides  something  else,  signifies  present 
time  ;  but  the  others,  that  which  is  about  the  present  time. 
Verbs  therefore  so  called,  by  themselves,  are  nouns,  and  have 

a  certain  signification,  for  the  speaker  establishes 
properly  nouns.   tne  conception, 2  and  the  hearer  acquiesces,  but  they 

do  not  yet  signify  3  whether  a  thing  "  is  "  or  "  is 
not,"  for  neither  is  "  to  be"  or  "not  to  be"  a  sign  of  a  thing, 

Logic ;  also  Pacius  de  Interp.,  c.  3.  The  ovo/xa  is  aviv  xpovov,  the  verb 
Trpod(jr]fiaivii  xQ0V°v  '■  this  distinction  is  lost  by  those  who,  with  Aldrich, 
resolve  the  verb  into  copula  and  predicate.  Vide  Ammonius  Scholia,  p. 
105,  b.  29.  The  infinitive  is  not  included  under  "verb,"  for  it  is  a 
noun-substantive,  nor  the  participle,  which  is  a  noun-adjective,  neither 
can  the  former  ever  be  the  predicate,  except  when  another  infinitive  is 
the  subject.  Vide  Whately,  b.  ii.  c.  i.  §  3.  For  case  as  appertaining  to 
verbs,  see  post,  ch.  20.  By  Aristotle,  number,  tense,  and  mood,  were  all 
reckoned  cases,  tttuxsuq,  or  fallings,  of  the  noun  and  verb,  so  our  Eng- 
lish word  "  fall  "  in  music. 

1  Boeth.  translates  aopiarov,  infinitum.  The  translation  is  blamed  by 
Vives  de  Caus.  Corr.  Art.  lib.  iii.  Sir  W.  Hamilton  uses  the  word  in- 
designate. 

2  That  is,  in  the  mind  of  the  hearer.  The  expression  'ivrrjoi  T-qv  Sta- 
voiav  is  rendered  by  Taylor  "  stops  the  discursive  power  " — a  meaning 
which  is  however  equivalent  to  "  establishes  the  conception,"  since 
ciavoia  being  properly  the  movement  of  the  intellect  towards  investi- 
gating truth,  is  "arrested,"  when  a  conception  is  fixed  upon  it:  thus 
Buhle,  "  constituit  conceptionem."  Taylor's  translation  is  strictly  exact, 
but  besides  being  obscure,  enforces  the  introduction  of  many  words  into 
the  text.  Aiavoid.  is  more  nearly  akin  to  logical  discursus  than  to  any 
•other  energy  :  see  the  note  upon  Anal.  Post,  lib.  i.  ch.  33. 

3  i.  e.  before  they  are  enunciatively  joined  with  nouns. 


CHAP.  IV.  1  ON   INTERPRETATION  51 

nor  if  you  should  say  merely,  "  bein^r,"  for  that  *■  They  are  in- 

,,/  ,  •       m?     v  i       -j  significant  ex- 

is  nothing  ;  they  signify  however,  besides  some-  cept  mcompo- 

thing  else,   a  certain   composition,   which  with-  Sltl0n- 

out    the   composing   members    it    is   impossible  to    under- 
stand.1 

Chap.  IV. — Of  the  Sentence.2 

A  sentence  is  voice  significant  by  compact,*  of  ,   Definiti 
which  any  part  separately  possesses  signification,    of  the  sentence 
as  indeed  a  word,  yet  not  as  affirmation  or  nega-   •'KtX'a,'am«i,- 
tion;  now  I  say  for  example  "man"  is  signifi-    ^.omitted  by 
cant,  but  does  not  imply   that  it    "  is  "   or    "  is 
not;"3    it   will   however  be  affirmation  or  negation,  if  any 
thing  be  added  to  it.     One/ syllable  of  the  word  uvBpunog, 
is   not   however  (significant),4  neither   the    "  vg "  in   "  pig," 
but  it  is  now  merely  sound ;  still  in  compound  words  a  part 
is  significant,  but  not  by  itself,  as  we  have  observed. 

Now  every  sentence  is  significant,  not  as  an  instrument,  but, 
as  we  have  said,  by  compact,  still  not  every  sentence  is  enunci- 
ative,5  but  that  in  which  truth  or  falsehood  is  inherent,  which 
things  do  not  exist  in  all  sentences,  as  prayer  is  a  sentence, 
but  it  is  neither  true  nor  false.     Let  therefore  the   „  _t. 

,  i        t        •         i      i     •  2-  Other  kinds 

other  sentences  be  dismissed,  their  consideration   of  sentence  t>e- 
belongs  more  properly  to   Rhetoric  or  Poetry;   ^wc— Logic" 
but    the   enunciative   sentence    to   our    present   conversant 

.i  with  the  enun- 

ttieoiy.  ciative  alone. 

1  Cf.  Mansel's  Prol.  Log.  p.  63.  I  follow  Waitz  and  Bulile;  Taylor's 
rendering  is  altogether  erroneous. 

2  Compare  Poetics,  ch.  '20;  also  this  treatise,  ch.  5;  Analy.  Post,  lib. 
ii.  cap.  10;  Metap.  vii.  4;  also  Aldrich,  sub  vocis  speciebus. 

3  That  is,  it  neither  affirms  nor  denies  something ;  a  verb  must  be 
added  to  make  it  significant. 

4  In  the  Poetics,  c.  20,  he  defines  a  syllable,  a  sound  without  signifi- 
cation, composed  of  a  mute  and  an  element  which  has  sound,  (i.  e.  a 
vowel  or  semi-vowel).  An  article,  again,  is  a  sound  insignificant,  showing 
the  finals  or  distinctions  of  a  word.  Buckley  has  well  called  the  de- 
scription most  obscure  :  Aristotle,  the  star  of  definition,  is  at  last  confused 
by  his  own  ray  ! 

5  ' AtrotyavTiKoq  8k  ov  nag.  The  quality  of  signifying  either  what  is 
true  or  false  is  the  logical  property  of  proposition,  and  is  the  immediate 
consequence  of  its  difference,  namely,  affirmation  or  negation.  Hill's 
Logic,  p.  90.  Vide  also  Whately,  Aldrich,  and  the  other  treatises  on 
Logic. 

e  2 


52  aristotles  organon.  [chap.  v. 


Chap.  V. —  Of  Enunciation? 

1.  Divisions  of  ^NE  nrs*  enunciative  sentence2   is  affirmation; 
the  enunciative   afterwards  negation,  and  all  the  rest  are  one  by 

sentence — \6-  •  ,.  T,    .  ,  ., 

roc  uitoipovTi-      conjunction.     It  is  necessary  however  that  every 
***'  enunciative  sentence  should  be  from  a  verb,  or 

from  the  case  of  a  verb,  for  the  definition  of  "  man,"  unless 
"  is,"  or  "  was,"  or  "  will  be,"  or  something  of  this  kind,  be 
added,  is  not  yet  an  enunciative  sentence.  Why  indeed  is  the 
sentence  "  a  terrestrial  biped  animal "  one  thing,  and  not  many 
things  ?  for  it  will  not  be  one,  because  it  is  consecutively  pro- 
nounced :  this  however  belongs  to  another  discussion.3  One 
enunciative  sentence,  moreover,  is  either  that  which  signifies 
one  thing,4  or  which  is  one  by  conjunction,5  and 
composite.01  many  (such  sentences)  are  either  those  which  sig- 
nify many  things6  and  not  one  thing,  or  which 
are  without  conjunction.7  Let  therefore  a  noun  or  a  verb  be 
only  a  word,  since  we  cannot  say  that  he  enunciates  who  thus 

1  Cum  disseramus  de  oratione  cujus  varlae  species  sunt — est  una  inter 
has  ad  propositum  potissima  qua?  pronuntiabilis  appellatur,  absolutam 
sententiam  comprehendens,  sola  ex  omnibus  verilati  at  falsitati  obnoxia, 
quam  vocat  Sergius,  "  effatum,"  Varro,  " proloquium,"  Cicero,  "  enunci- 
atum,"  Grace  "  protasin,"  turn  "axioma;  " — familiarius  tamen  dicetur 
"propositio." — Apuleius  de  Dogm.  Platonis,  lib.  iii.  As  Mansel  ob- 
serves justly,  he  has  not  distinguished  between  airofpavaig  and  Trporacng. 
the  former  of  which  is  rendered  by  Boethius  "  enunciatio,"  the  latter  "pro- 
positio."  Vide  Elem.  sect.  2,  Trendelenburg ;  Aquinas,  Opusc.  48,  Tract, 
de  Enunc.  The  distinction  drawn  by  the  latter  is  not  implied  by  Aris- 
totle either  here  or  Anal.  Pr.  i.  1,  2. 

2  Aoyof  anotyavTiKOQ.  Oratio  indicativa,  Pet.  Hispanus.  Boethius, 
"  Oratio  enunciativa."  F or  Kara^aaig,  &c.  see  next  chapter.  Aldrich's  de- 
finition errs  against  the  third  rule,  and  hardly  presses  on  the  second — for 
good  definition. 

3  Definition  is  a  sentence,  but  not  as  if  one  enunciation ;  its  consider- 
ation belongs  to  the  first  philosophy,  and  the  reader  will  find  the  question 
solved  in  lib.  6,  of  the  Metaphysics. 

4  As  "  a  man  runs,"  the  purely  categorical. 

5  This  may  be  disjunctive,  which  is  a  species  of  hypothetical  or  com- 
pound, as  "  it  is  either  day  or  night."  Vide  Whately,  book  ii.  ch.  ii. 
sect.  1. 

6  These  come  under  the  class  ambiguous,  founded  often  on  one  equi- 
vocal term  only,  as  the  "  dog  is  moved,"  where  dog  may  signify  many 
things. 

7  As  "  I  congratulate  you,"  &c.  Compare  Hill  and  Whately ;  in  the 
former  many  examples  are  given. 


CHAP.  VI.]  ON   INTERPRETATION.  53 

expresses  any  thing  by  his  voice  whether  he  is  *  i.  e.  simple 

interrogated  by  any  one  or  not,  but  that  he  speaks  ^™atsii°I^"  le 

from  deliberate  intention.1     Now  of  these  enun-  negation. 

ciations  one  is  simple,  for  instance  something  of  *  \*y\  not  n^ht." 

something,  or  fromt  something,  but  another  is  3-  Definition 

,°    i>  ,1  j.  i    •  i  i  •   i    •       of  simple  enun- 

composed  of  these,;}:  as  a  certain  sentence  which  is  datum,  amavT- 
already  a  composite  ;  simple  enunciation,  then,  is  ?£jrepe'I™" 
voice   significant   about   something  being    inhe- 
rent, or  non-inherent,  according  as  times  are  di-  §  i.e.  into  past, 

.  ,    ,   P0  present,  and  fu- 

Vlded.CJ  a  ture. 

Chap.  VI. — Of  Affirmation  and  Negation.3 

Affirmation  is   the  enunciation  of  something   1.  Distinctive 
concerning  something,  but  negation  is  the  enun-   ^l6™*1?.",,0^ 

?  .  a  o  affirmation  (xa. 

ciation    of  something   from   something.4     Since,   ™0a<nr)  and 

1  This  form  arises  from  our  usual  elliptical  method  of  expression,  in 
regard  to  interrogatives,  when  the  repeated  verb  is  understood  but  not 
expressed ;  as,  "  Who  reads  ?  Socrates,"  i.  e.  "  Socrates  reads." 

2  These  sentences  are  known  by  the  barbarous  name  of  propositions 
de  inesse,  that  is,  denoting  the  inherency  or  inbeing  of  the  predicated  qua- 
lity in  the  class  or  thing  expressed  by  the  subject.  The  expression 
tov  virapxtiv  in  Aristotle,  has  two  meanings,  one  in  which  the  pre- 
dicate is  said  to  be  in  the  subject,  which  is  equivalent  to  Karijyopnrai, 
as  all  B  is  A,  to  A  Karriyopilrai  Kara  iravroq  roii  B  ;  and  Elvai  iv, 
whereby  the  subject  is  said  to  be  in  the  predicate,  as  all  A  is  B,  A  iariv  iv 
o\y  ry  B.,  which  is  exactly  the  reverse  of  Karriyopelrai.  See  note  3, 
p.  80.  On  the  different  species  of  sentences  alluded  to  in  the  above 
chapter,  see  also  Petrus  Hispanus,  Sum.  Log.  Tract  1.  "  Vocum  signifi- 
cativarum  ad  "placitum,  alia  complexa  ut  oratio,  alia  incomplexa  ut 
nomen  et  verbum.  Orationum  perfectarum,  alia  indicativa,  ut  '  Homo 
currit ; '  alia  imperativa,  ut '  Petre  fac  ignem  ; '  alia  optativa,  ut  "  Utinam 
esset  bonus  clericus  !  "  alia  subjunctiva,  ut  "  si  veneris  ad  me  dabo  tibi 
equum  ;  "  alia  deprecativa,  ut  "  miserere  mei  Deus !  "  Harum  autem 
orationum  sola  indicativa  oratio  dicitur  esse  propositio."  Cf.  Boeth.  de 
Syll.  Cat.  p.  582,  also  Poet.  c.  20. 

3  Upon  the  import  of  Propositions,  see  Mill's  Logic,  book  i.  ch.  5 
Reid  defines  judgment  after  the  above  manner :  "  an  act  of  the  mind 
whereby  one  thing  is  affirmed  or  denied  of  another."  Affirmative  judg- 
ment is  called  by  Aldrich,  "  compositio,"  negative,  "  divisio,"  (rvv9tcng 
and  diaiptaig  :  comp.  1st  ch.  of  this  treatise.  Apuleius  calls  the  sentence 
either  Propositio  dedicativa  or  abdicativa. 

4  My  translation  is  identical  with  that  of  Boethius :  Aldrich's  defini- 
tion is  applicable  only  to  propositions  "  tertii  adjaceniis,"  and  is  in  fact  acci- 
dental. Vide  Huyshe,  p.  5t. 


5-i  Aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  vn. 

negation  (aTro-    however,  a  man  may  enunciate  what  is  inherent  as 
*a<7,t')  though  it  were  not,1  and  what  is  not  2  as  though  it 

were  ;  that  which  is,  as  if  it  were,  and  that  which  is  not,  as  if  it 
were  not,  and  in  like  manner  about  times  external  to  the  pre- 
sent ;  it  is  possible  that  whatever  any  one  affirms  may  be 
denied,  and  that  whatever  any  one  denies  may  be  affirmed, 
whence  it  is  evident  that  to  every  affirmation  there  is  an  op- 
posite negation,  and  to  every  negation  an  opposite  affirma- 
tion.3 Let  this  be  contradiction,  affirmation  and 
betweenaffim-  negation  being  opposites,4  but  I  call  that  opposi- 
ative  and  nega-   tion  which  is  of  the  same  respecting  the  same,5  not 

tive  constitutes  .  ,.  ,  ,  ,    *  ~.      ,  /»      , 

contradiction      equivocally,   and  such  other  particulars  ot   the 
uirn'fMunr).  cf.   jjjn(j  as   we  have  concluded   against  sophistical 
importunities.6 

Chap.  VII. — Of  Contraries  and  Contradictories. 

Of  things,  since  some  are  universal,  but  others 
between^he"1  singular,7  (and  by  universal  I  mean  whatever  may 
universal  (to     naturallv  be  predicated  of  many  things,  but  by  sin- 

KaDoXov)  1  ji      i        i  ■•    1  it  n  •  •  i 

and  the  singu-    gular,  that  which  may  not :  as  "  man    is  universal, 

«»"►"""       but  "  Callias "  singular,)  it  is  necessary  to  enunciate 

that  something  is,  or  is  not,  inherent,  at  one  time,  in 

'  A  false  negation,  (2)  a  false  affirmation  :  of  the  subsequent  examples, 
the  first  is  a  true  affirmation,  and  the  second  a  true  negation. 

3  This  classification  originates  in  the  logical  difference  of  propositions, 
see  Hill's  Logic,  page  96. 

4  al  avriKei^isvai  (irporacreig),  this  term  is  sometimes  by  Aristotle 
limited  to  contradictories. 

5  "  When  having  the  same  subject  and  predicate  they  differ  in  quan- 
tity, or  quality,  or  both."  Whately.  Vide  also  some  general  remarks  on 
this  subject  in  Huyshe,  p.  51,  note. 

6  Vide  "  Sophistical  Elenchi." 

7  Taylor  has  mistaken  Ka9'  tKaarov,  by  translating  it  "  particular,"  as 
usual :  see  note,  page  33.  Compare  An.  Pr.  i.  1,2.  Omnis  is  the  sign  of 
an  universal  proposition  taken  distinctively,  as  Omnis  homo  est  animal ; 
when  collectively,  the  proposition  is  singular.  Individual  names  are 
distinguished  as  individua  signata,  as  "  Socrates  :  "  individua  demonstra- 
tiva,  by  a  demonstrative  pronoun,  hie  homo  :  individua  vaga,  by  an  inde- 
finite pronoun,  aliquis,  quidam :  this  distinction  is  found  in  the  Greek 
commentators.  Cf.  Albert  de  Predicab.  Tract,  iv.  cap.  7.  Aquinas. 
The  two  first  form  singular  propositions ;  a  doubt  has  been  entertained 
as  to  the  last,  whether  they  form  singulars  or  particulars.     Mansel's  Logic, 


CHAP.  VII.]  ON   INTERPRETATION.  55 

an  universal,  at  another  in  a  singular  thing.  Now,  if  any  one 
universally  enunciates  of  an  universal,  that  something  is  or  is 
not  inherent,  these  enunciations  will  be  contrary  : 1 
I  mean  universally  enunciates  of  an  universal,  as  contrariety— 
that  "  every  man  is  white,"  "  no  man  is  white."  ¥avT1?'  al 
When  on  the  other  hand  he  enunciates  of  univer- 
sals,  not  universally,2  these  are  not  contraries,  though  the 
things  signified  may  sometimes  be  contrary  ;  but  I  mean  by  not 
universally  enunciating  of  universals,  as  that  "  man  is  white," 
"man  is  not  white  :"  for  man  being  universal,  is  not  employed 
as  an  universal  in  the  enunciation,  since  the  word  "  every " 
does  not  signify  the  universal,  but  (shows  that  the  subject  is)  uni- 
versally (taken).  Now  to  predicate  universally  of  what  is  univer- 
sally predicated  is  not  true,  for  no  affirmation  will  be  true  in  which 
the  universal  is  predicated  of  an  universal  predicate,3  as  for  in- 
stance, "every  man"  is  "every  animal."  Where-  3  0fcontradic 
fore  I  say  affirmation  is  opposed  to  negation  contra-  tion :  {hrtubarX- 
dictorily,  the  affirmation  which  signifies  the  uni-  «"•»»*««'»<»>■ 
versal  to  that  which  is  not  universal,  as  "  every  man  is  white," 
"not  every  man  is  white,"  "no  man  is  white,"  "some  man  is 
white."  But  contrarily  is  between  universal  affirmative  and  uni- 
versal negative,  as  "  every  man  is  white,"  "  no  man  is  white," 
"  every  man  is  just,"  "no  man  is  just."  4  Wherefore  it  is  impossi- 

p.  46.  When  a  singular  term  is  the  predicate,  it  must  of  course  be  co- 
extensive with  its  subject.  On  the  above  chapter  compare  Whately, 
book  ii.  2,  3,  and  Hill,  9,  et  seq. :  in  fact,  a  slight  acquaintance  even 
with  Aldrich's  -Logic  will  suffice  to  place  the  principle  of  opposition, 
as  copied  here,  clearly  before  the  reader ;  for  mere  simplification  we 
have  annexed  the  usual  scheme  of  opposition. 

1  That  is,  adds  the  universal  mark,  or  sign,  "  every  "  or  "  none."  It 
should  be  recollected  also,  as  Taylor  observes  here,  "  that  contraries  may 
at  one  and  the  same  time  be  absent  from  a  subject,  but  they  cannot  at 
one  and  the  same  time  be  inherent  in  it;"  this  Aristotle  indeed  points 
out  in  this  chapter.  (2)  "  Not  universally,  i.  e.  does  not  add  the  universal 
mark" — he  adds,  "  the  things  signified  may  be  contraries,  that  is  to  say, 
the  mental  conceptions  may  be,  whilst  the  enunciations  are  still  indefi- 
nite. The  extent  of  the  indefinite  is  regulated  by  the  matter  of  the  pro- 
position, and  is  universal  in  necessary  and  impossible  matter." 

3  For  example,  to  say,  every  man  is  every  animal,  is  false,  unless  man  is 
horse,  ox,  etc. ;  or  to  say  every  man  is  every  visible  thing  will  be  false,  be- 
cause the  predicate  of  every  man  may  be  also  said  of  Socrates,  hence  So- 
crates would  be  every  thing  visible.  Socrates  would  therefore  be  Plato, 
and  Aristotle,  and  every  thing  visible,  which  is  absurd. — Taylor. 

4  These  contraries  cannot  be  at  one  and  the  same  time  true,  but  they  may 
be  both  false,  or  one  true,  and  the  other  false.     In  necessary  matter,  at* 


56  Aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  vti. 

ble  that  these  should  at  one  and  the  same  time  be 

4.  Contraries        ,  u     ,  ,,  ..  . 

themselves        true,  but  the  opposites  to  these  may  sometimes  pos- 
caiinot  at  the     sibly  be  co- verified  about  the  same  thing,  as  that 

eiiniC  time  DG  ,  ,  *3' 

true,  though         not  every  man  is  white,  and  "some  man  is  white."1 
their  opposites    0f  guch  contradictions  then  of  universals,  as  are 

universally  made,  one  must  necessarily  be  true  or 
false,  and  also  such  as  are  of  singulars,  as  "  Socrates  is 
white,"  "  Socrates  is  not  white  ; "  but  of  such  contradictions 
as  are  indeed  of  universals,  yet  are  not  universally  made,  one 
is  not  always  true,  but  the  other  false.  For  at  one  and  the 
same  time  we  may  truly  say  that  "  man  is  white,"  and  that 
"  man  is  not  white,"  and  "  man  is  handsome,"  and  "  man  is 
not  handsome,"  for  if  he  is  deformed  he  is  not  handsome, 
and  if  any  thing  is  becoming  to  be,  it  is,  not.  This  how- 
ever may  at  once  appear  absurd,  because  the  assertion  "  man 
is  not  white,"  seems  at  the  same  time  to  signify  the  same 
thing,  as  "  no  man  is  white,"  but  it  neither  necessarily  signi- 
fies the  same  thing,  nor  at  the  same  time.2 
5.  one  nega-  Notwithstanding  it  is  evident  that  of  one  af- 

tion  incident      firmation  there  is  one  negation,  for  it  is  necessary 

Urinatives  are  true,  negatives  false,  in  impossible  matter  negatives  true, 
affirmatives  false,  in  contingent  matter  both  false.  Properly  speaking,  it 
is  contrary  to  the  very  nature  of  logical  inquiry  to  admit  any  reference 
whatever  to  the  understood  matter  of  proposition,  of  which  Logic  can  take 
no  cognizance,  its  province  being,  to  establish  argument  when  necessarily 
deducible  from  propositions  placed  in  a  certain  connexion.  From  the 
truth  of  the  universal  or  the  falsehood  of  the  singular  we  infer  the  accidental 
quality  of  all  the  opposed  propositions  ;  but  from  the  falsehood  of  an  uni- 
versal or  truth  of  a  singular,  we  only  know  the  quality  of  the  contradictory. 

1  He  means  "  singular  sub-contraries,"  which  contradict  the  universals 
mutually  contrary  to  each  other,  hence  are  co-verified  in  the  same  thing, 
i.  e.  in  contingent  matter,  as  in  the  above  instance.  The  expression  sub- 
contrary  ({nrtvavriojg)  is  not  used  by  Aristotle,  though  he  admits  the  op- 
position above ;  he  calls  it  in  Anal.  Prior,  ii.  15,  an  opposition  Kara  rrjv 
X'tliv,  but  not  Kar  akijOtiav.  subalterns  (vira\\r)\oi)  are  not  noticed 
by  Aristotle,  the  first  who  gave  the  laws  of  this  species  of  opposition  was 
Apuleius  De  Dogmate  Platonis,  lib.  iii.,  who  was  followed  by  Marcianus 
Capella,  and  Boethius.  The  three  kinds  of  opposition  are  called  by  the 
earlier  writers,  Alterutrae,  Incongrus,  and  Suppares. 

2  Viz.  what  he  has  said,  that  indefinites  are  at  one  and  the  same  time 
true.  Indefinite  enunciation  may  seem  to  be  universal,  because  it  has  an 
universal  subject,  but  it  is  not  universal,  because  it  wants  the  universal 
mark,  "  every  "  or  "no  one."  It  is  not  requisite  that  the  universal  and 
indefinite  should  be  at  one  and  the  same  time  true  nor  false,  for  one  may 
be  true  and  the  other  false. 


CHAP.  VII.*] 


ON    INTERPRETATION. 


57 


that  tbe  negation  should  deny  the  same  thing  toeachaffirm- 
which  the  affirmation  affirmed,  and  also  from  the  atl0n- 
same,  (i.  e.)  either  from  some  singular  or  some  universal,  uni- 
versally or  not  universally  ;  I  say,  for  instance,  that  "  Socrates 
is  white,"  "  Socrates  is  not  white."  If  however  there  is 
something  else  from  the  same  thing,  or  the  same  thing  from 
something  else,  that  (enunciation)  will  not  be  opposite,  but 
different  from  it ; '  to  the  one,  "  every  man  is  white,"  the  other 
(is  opposed)  "  not  every  man  is  white,"  and  to  the  one,  "  a  cer- 
tain man  is  white,"  the  other,  "  no  man  is  white  ;"  and  to  the 
one,  "  man  is  white,"  the  other,  "  man  is  not  white." 

That  there  is  then  one  affirmation  contradictorily  opposed  to 
one  negation,  and  what  these  are,  has  been  shown,  also  that  there 
are  other  contraries,  and  what  they  are,  and  that  not  every  con- 
tradiction is  true  or  false,  and  why  and  when  it  is  true  or  false. 

1  That  is,  if  the  negative  differs  from  the  affirmative  in  the  predicate  or 
the  subject.  The  instance  "  Socrates  is  white,"  Socrates  is  not  white, 
is  contradictory,  the  one  being  true  always,  and  the  other  false  ;  which  con- 
stitutes the  essential  feature  of  contradictories  included  in  the  definition 
given  Anal.  Post,  i.  2,  ' Avr'npaaiQ  6k  avTiQiaiQ  i/c  oi»K  tort  fitra^v  tcaff 
avri)v.  Some  logicians  call  the  opposition  of  singulars  "  secondary  con- 
tradiction." Vide  Boethius,  p.  613.  Wallis,  lib.  ii.  c.  5.  For  the  rules 
of  contradiction,  vide  Aldrich,  Whately,  Huyshe.  The  following  scheme 
from  Aldrich  gives  the  opposition  of  necessary,  impossible,  and  contingent 
matter  (n.  i.  c.)  as  to  universal  contraries  A.  E.,  and  sub-contraries  I.  and 
O.,  with  their  verity  (v.)  or  falsity  (f.).    See  also  scheme  page  3. 


Subcontraries 


58  aristotle's  organon.       [chap.  viii.  ix. 


Chap.  VIII. —  Of  Opposition  when  there  is  not  one  Affirmation, 

nor  one  Negation} 

,   m.  The  affirmation  and  negation  are  one,  which  indi- 

1.  What  con-  . 

Btitutes  single     cate  one  thing  of  one,  either  of  an  universal,  being 
affirmation  and   taken  universally,  or  in  like  manner  if  it  is  not,  as 

negation,  is  the  J '  ' 

unity  of  the  "every  man  is  white,'  "  not  every  man  is  white," 
theJpredicate°  "  man  is  white,"  "man  is  not  white,"  "no  man  is 
without  equi-  white,"  "  some  man  is  white,"  if  that  which  is 
white  signifies  one  thing.  But  if  one  name  be 
given  to  two  tilings,  from  which  one  thing  does  not  arise,  there 
is  not  one  affirmation  nor  one  negation  ;2  as  if  any  one  gave 
the  name  "  garment "  to  a  "horse,"  and  to  "a  man;"  that 
"  the  garment  is  white,"  this  will  not  be  one  affirmation,  nor 
one  negation,  since  it  in  no  respect  differs  from  saying  "  man  " 
and  "  horse  "  are  "  white,"  and  this  is  equivalent  to  "  man  is 
white,"  and  "  horse  is  white."  If  therefore  these  signify  many 
things,  and  are  many,  it  is  evident  that  the  first  enunciation 
either  signifies  many  things  or  nothing,3  for  "  some  man  is  not 
a  horse,"  wherefore  neither  in  these  is  it  necessary  that  one 
should  be  a  true,  but  the  other  a  false  contradiction.4 

,  .     .       Chap.  IX. — Of  Opposition  in  contingent  Futures. 

In  those  things  which  are,  and  have  been,5  the 
past  affirms-  affirmation  and  negation  must  of  necessity  be  true 
tionmustneces-  or  fa^se  5  *n  universals,  as  universals,  always  one 
saniy  be  true  true  but  the  other  false,  and  also  in  singulars,  as 
otherwise  in  we  have  shown  ;  but  in  the  case  of  universals  not 
respect  of  the      universally  enunciated,  there  is  no  such  necessity, 

and  concerning  these  we  have  also  spoken,  but  as 

1  Vide  Whately,  b.  ii.  c.  2,  sect.  3. 

2  That  is,  enunciation  is  equivocal. 

3  "  The  garment  is  white  "  signifies  many  things,  i.  e.  if  the  word 
"  garment"  be  assumed  for  "man  "  and  "horse;"  or  it  signifies  nothing, 
that  is,  if  it  is  sc  assumed  as  to  signify  one  thing,  since  being  taken  for 
man,  horse,  the  latter  is  not  one  thing,  but  nothing. 

4  For  both  may  be  true,  as  every  garment  (i.  e.  man)  is  rational,  not 
every  garment  (i.  e.  horse)  is  rational;  or  they  may  be  both  false. 

5  Taylor  reads  ywofitvtov,  after  the  Laurentian  MS.  Waitz,  Bekker, 
and  Buhle  ytvofih'wv.  In  iis  quae  sunt  et  quie  facta  sunt.  Averrois. 
Of  course  Aristotle  does  not  mean  by  the  assertion  in  the  text,  other  than 
that  one  is  true  and  the  other  false. 


CHAP.  IX  __  ON    INTERPRETATION.  59 

to  singulars  and  futures,  this  is  not  the  case.  For  if  every 
affirmation  or  negation  be  true  or  false,  it  is  also  necessary 
that  every  thing  should  exist  or  should  not  exist,  for  if  one 
man  says  that  a  thing  Avill  be,  but  another  denies  the  same, 
one  of  them  must  evidently  of  necessity  speak  truth,  if  every 
affirmation  or  negation  be  true  or  false,  for  both  will  not 
subsist  in  such  things  at  one  and  the  same  time.  Thus  if 
it  is  true  to  say  that  "  a  thing  is  white,"  or  that  "  it  is  not 
white,"  it  must  of  necessity  be  "white"  or  not  "white,"  and 
if  it  is  white  or  not  white,  it  wa3  true  to  affirm  or  to  deny  it  : 
also  if  it  is  not,  it  is  falsely  said  to  be,  and  if  it  is  falsely 
said  to  be,  it  is  not  ;  so  that  it  is  necessary  that  either 
the  affirmation  or  the  negation  should  be  true  or  false.  In- 
deed there  is  nothing  which  either  is,  or  is  gene- 

9      WVi    t 

rated  fortuitously,  nor  casually,  nor  will  be,  or  trueaffirma- 

not  be,  but  all  things  are  from  necessity,  and  not  M0"  ?r  nesa- 

casually,  for  either  he  who  affirms  speaks  truth,  futures  ex- 

or  he  who  denies,  for  in  like  manner  it  might  clu.d5s  casual 

°  existence. 

either  have  been  or  not  have  been,  lor  that  which 

subsists   casually  neither  does  nor  will  subsist  more  in  this 

way  than  in  that.1     Moreover  if  a  thing  is  now  "white,"  it 

1  Pluribus  modis  Aristoteles  repetit  et  inculcat  quod  si  aut  affirmatio  aut 
negatio  necessario  sit  vera  de  rebus  futuris  item  e  veritate  in  dicendo 
colligi  possit  quomodo  res  ipsae  evenire  debeant  atque  ex  ipsis  rebus  ju- 
dicetur  quid  sit  verum,  quid  falsum  :  etenim  si  certum  est  et  derinitum 
utrum  verum  sit,  utrum  falsum  in  iis  quae  de  rebus  futuris  pronuntiantur, 
prsestituta  sunt  omnia,  et  qua?  eveniunt,  necessario  eveniunt.  Waitz.  It 
is  well  observed  by  Ammonius,  that  the  observations  here  made  by  Aristo- 
tle "  are  conversant  not  only  with  logic,  but  with  every  part  of  philosophy." 
Not  all  things  are  assumed  to  exist  from  necessity,  but  some  are  supposed 
to  be  in  our  own  power;  this  constitutes  the  doctrine  of  moral  responsibi- 
lity with  the  theologian,  the  scientific  investigation  of  the  philosopher,  and 
the  division  into  necessary  and  contingent  of  the  logician :  with  respect 
to  the  last,  the  inquiry  here  seems  to  be  whether  all  contradiction  defi- 
nitely or  only  indefinitely  comprehends  these.  The  fatalist  looks  to  the  doc- 
trine of  necessity  as  authorizing  his  "  affections  and  antipathies  "  to  become 
"the  laws  ruling  his  moral  state,"  (Vide  Shelley's  Queen  Mab,)  forgetful  of 
the  moral  faculty  of  self-approval  and  the  contrary,  (SoKifiaariid))  and 
{diroSoKifiaGTiKi)) ,  admitted  by  Epictetus,  (Arr.  Epict.  lib.  i.  Capt.  1,) 
whilst  others  are  led  by  it  into  the  "  visionary  presumption  of  a  peculiar 
destiny."  Vide  Foster's  Essays  on  the  Epithet  Romantic.  For  the 
Ethical  discussion  of  the  subject,  the  reader  is  referred  to  Butler's  Ana- 
logy, and  so  far  as  certain  laws  of  thought  form  the  basis  of  logical  ne- 
cessity, he  will  find  an  admirable  paper  in  chap.  vi.  of  Mansel's  Prolego- 
mena  Logica.     It   is  sufficient  for  our  present  purpose  to  state  that 


60  ARISTOTLE'S   ORGANON.  [CHAP.  IX. 

was  true  to  say  before  that  it  will  be  "white,"  so  that  it 
was  always  true  to  say  of  any  thing  generated  that  it 
either  is,  or  that  it  will  be ;  but  if  it  was  always  true  to 
say  that  it  is,  or  will  be,  it  is  impossible  that  this  is  not, 
nor  should  be ;  and  whatever  must  of  necessity  be,  it  is 
impossible  that  it  should  not  have  been  generated,  and  what 
it  is  impossible  should  not  have  been  generated  must  of  ne- 
cessity have  been  generated  ;  wherefore  all  things  that  will 
be,  it  is  necessary  should  be  generated,  and  hence  there  will 
be  nothing  casual  nor  fortuitous,  for  if  it  were  fortuitous  it 
would  not  be  of  necessity.  Nor  is  it  possible  to  say,  that 
neither  of  them  is  true,  as  that  it  will  neither  be,  nor  will  not 
be,  for  in  the  first  place  the  affirmation  being  false,  the  nega- 
3.  Result  of  ^on  Wi^  not  De  true>  and  this  being  false,  it  re- 
denying  the       suits  that  the  affirmation  is  not  true.     And  besides, 

truth  of  both.       .«  .,  ,,  ,,  .         .         .    ,, 

it  it  were  true  to  say  that  a  thing  is  at  the  same 
time  "  white  "  and  "  great,"  both  must  of  necessity  be,  but  if 
it  shall  be  to-morrow,  it  must  necessarily  be  to-morrow,  and  if 
it  will  neither  be  nor  will  not  be  to-morrow,  it  will  not  be  a 
casual  thing,  for  example,  a  naval  engagement,  for  it  would  be 
.  requisite  that  the  engagement  should  neither  oc- 

cur nor  not  occur. 

These  and  similar  absurdities  then  will  hap- 
surdity  follows  pen,  if  of  every  affirmation  and  negation,  whether 
tnencasuaiins  *n  resPec*  °f  universals  enunciated  universally,  or 
of  singulars,  it  is  necessary  that  one  of  the  op- 
posites  be  true  and  the  other  false,  but  that  nothing  happens 
casually  in  those  things  which  subsist,  but  that  all  are,  and 
are  generated  of  necessity  ;  so  that  it  will  neither  be  necessary 
to  deliberate  nor  to  trouble  ourselves,  as  if  we  shall  do  this 
thing,  something  definite  will  occur,  but  if  we  do  not,  it  will 
not  occur.  For  there  is  nothing  to  prevent  a  person  for  ten 
thousand  years  asserting  that  this  will  happen,  and  another 
person  denying  it,  so  that  of  necessity  it  will  have  been  then 
true  to  assert  either  of  them.  And  it  makes  no  difference 
whether  any  persons  have  uttered  a  contradiction  or  not,  for 

Aristotle  traces  here  the  institution  of  a  word  to  the  primary  concept  of 
the  thing,  so  that  if  affirmation  is  true,  a  thing  is,  if  negation  is  true,  a 
thing  is  not.  If  either  be  true  or  false,  he  who  affirms  or  denies  says  truly 
or  falsely,  so  that  if  affirmative  be  true  or  false,  a  thing  must  necessarily 
exist  or  not  exist.  He  alleges  two  enthymematic  proofs,  terminating  in  a 
reductio  ad  absu  -dum. 


CHAP.  IX.]  ON    INTERPRETATION.  61 

it  is  evident  that  the  things  are  so,  although  the  one  should 
not  have  affirmed  any  thing,  or  the  other  have  denied  it,  since 
it  is  not,  because  it  has  been  affirmed  or  denied,  that  therefore 
a  thing  will  or  will  not  be,  neither  will  it  be  more  so  for  ten 
thousand  years  than  for  any  time  whatever.  Hence  if  a 
thing  so  subsisted  in  every  time  that  one  of  these  is  truly 
asserted  of  it,  it  was  necessary  that  this  should  take  place ; 
and  each  thing  generated,  always  so  subsisted,  as  to  have  been 
generated  from  necessity,  for  when  any  one  truly  said  that  it 
will  be,  it  was  not  possible  not  to  have  been  generated,  and  of 
that  which  is  generated,  it  was  always  true  to  say  that  it  will  be. 
But*  if  these  things  are  impossible  —  (for  *  vide  Bekter, 
we    see    that    there    is    a   beginningr    of  future   Waitz,  Buhie, 

o  o  ana  trie  -Ltipsic 

things,  both  from  our  deliberation  and  practice,  edition.  Tay- 
and  briefly  in  things  which  do  not  always  energize,  lor  omits  the  "• 
there  is  equally  a  power  of  being  and  of  not  being,  in 
which  both  to  be  and  not  to  be  occurs,  as  well  as  to  have  been 
generated  and  not  to  have  been  generated ;  and,  indeed,  we 
have  many  things  which  evidently  subsist  in  this  manner,  for 
example,  it  is  possible  for  this  garment  to  have  been  cut  in 
pieces,  and  it  may  not  be  cut  in  pieces,  but  be  worn  out  be- 
forehand, so  also  it  is  possible  that  it  may  not  be  cut  in  pieces, 
for  it  would  not  have  been  worn  out  before,  unless  it  had  been 
possible  that  it  might  not  be  cut  in  pieces,  and  so  also  in  re- 
spect of  other  productions,  which  are  spoken  of  according  to 
a  power  of  this  kind — )  then  it  is  evident  that  all  things 
neither  are,  nor  are  generated  of  necessity,  but  5.  Many  things 
that  some  things  subsist  casually,  and  that  their   have  a  casual 

.        .         ~  %     •  subsistence  as 

affirmation  is  not  more  true  than  their  negation,  and   to  the  nature  of 
that  there  are  others  in  which  one  of  these  subsists   don^rnegs^ 
more  frequently,  and  for  the  most  part,1  yet  so,  that   tion- 
either  might  possibly  have  occurred,but  the  other  not.2 

Wherefore,  being,  must  of  necessity  be  when  it  is,3 
and  non-being,  not  be,  when  it  is  not ;  but  it  is  not  ne- 
cessary that  every  being  should  be,  nor  that  non-being 
should  not  be,  since  it  is  not  the  same  thing  for  every  being 

1  As  for  instance,  finding  a  treasure ;  here  the  negation  is  oftener  true 
than  the  affirmation:  except  recently  in  California  and  Australia. 

2  That  is,  the  rarer  may  occur,  but  the  more  common  may  not. 

3  Hypothetically.  i.  e.  a  thing  must  be,  if  it  is  supposed  to  be,  because 
being  and  non-being  cannot  concur  in  eodem,  eodem  tempore. 


62  ARISTOTLE  S    OKGA.NON.  [CHAP.  IX. 

to  be  from  necessity,  when  it  is,  and  simply  to  be  from  neces- 
.  „     „  ,         sity,  and  in  like  manner  as  to  non-being.     There 

6.  Parallel  rea-    .     J"  .  .         .        .  °„ 

soning  as  to  is  the  same  reasoning  also  in  the  case  01  contra- 

and^difficuity  Miction ;  to  be  or  not  to  be  is  necessary  for  every 

as  to  the  neces-  thing,  also  that  it  shall,  or  shall  not  be,  yet  it  is  not 

falsehood  of*  requisite  to  speak  of  each  separately,  but  I  say, 

contingent  fu-  for  instance,  that  it  is  necessary  for  a  naval  action 

tures,  solved.  » 

to  occur  or  not  occur  to-morrow,  yet  it  is  not 
necessary  that  there  should  be  a  naval  action  to-morrow,  nor 
that  there  should  not  be ;  it  is  necessary,  however,  that  it 
should  either  be  or  not  be.  Wherefore,  since  assertions  and 
things  are  similarly  true,  it  is  evident  that  things  which  so 
subsist,  as  that  whatever  have  happened,  the  contraries  also 
were  possible,  it  is  necessary  that  contradiction  should  subsist 
in  the  same  manner,  which  happens  to  those  things  which  are 
not  always,  or  which  not  always,  are  not.  For  of  these,  one 
part  of  the  contradiction  must  necessarily  be  true  or  false,  not 
indeed  this  or  that,  but  just  as  it  may  happen,  and  one  must 
be  the  rather  true,  yet  not  already  true  nor  false ; 1  so  that  it 
is  evidently  not  necessary  that  of  every  affirmation  and  nega- 
tion of  opposites,  one  should  be  true,  but  the  other  filse  ; 2  for 
it  does  not  happen  in  the  same  manner  with  things  which  are 
not,  but  which  either  may  or  may  not  be,  as  with  things 
which  are,  but  it  happens  as  we  have  said  3 

1  When  the  contingents  of  course  are  unequal. 

2  That  is,  definitely. 

3  Quae  ex  casu  pendent  et  esse  possunt  et  non  esse ;  quare  in  his  affir- 
matio  et  negatio  (r)  avricpaaig)  quum  nihil  praestitutum  sit,  eodem  jure 
vera?  vel  falsae  pronuntiantur  ( 6  juoi'wc  i%ti)  altera  utra  enim  admittenda 
erit  neque  tamen,  altera  alteri  praeferenda,  tanquam  sit  destinatum,  et 
certum  quod  eventurum  sit ;  quamvis  enim  alteram  veram  fore  magis  sit 
probabile  quam  alteram  (/uaWov  aXrjOi))  nondum  vera  est  donee 
eventus  earn  comprobaverit.  Waitz.  Aristotle's  object,  whilst  he  admits 
the  contingent,  is  to  reduce  it,  for  all  logical  purposes,  to  a  necessary 
certainty  of  consequence.  The  whole  of  this  chapter  proves  at  once  the 
practical  turn  of  his  mind,  opposed  alike  to  the  ideal  of  Plato,  the  merely 
probable  (as  a  result)  of  the  Academics,  and  the  versatile  scepticism  of 
Pyrrho,  against  whom  Montaigne  ushers  in  his  own  Philippic  (Essay  12, 
book  ii.)  by  the  famous  quotation  from  Sextus  Err.piricus. 

"  Nil  sciri  si  quis  putat,  id  quoque  nescit 

An  sciri  possit  quo  se,  nil  sciri  fatetur." 
Compare  the  philosophical  principle  of  formal  necessity  in  this  chapter 
with  Bp.  Butler's  distinction  between,  "  by  necessity,"  and  acting  "neces- 
sarily," Analogy,  ch.  6,  also  his  Introduction,  and  part  ii.  ch.  2,  upon  the 
nature  of  the  contingent  and  proof. 


CHAP.  X._  ON   INTERPRETATION.  63 


Chap.  X. — Of  Opposition  with  the  addition  of  the  Copula.* 

Since  affirmation  signifies  something  of  something,  and  this 
is  either  a  noun,  or  anonymous,2  (i.  e.  indefinite,)  but  what  is 
in  affirmation  must  be  one  and  of  one  thing,3  all 
affirmation  and  negation  will  be  either  from  a  enmictatfon!  °* 
noun  and  a  verb,  or  from  an  indefinite  noun  and 
verb.  (But  what  a  noun  is,  and  what  the  anonymous,  has  been 
shown  before,  for  I  do  not  reckon  "  not  man  "  a  noun,  but  an 
indefinite  noun,  for  an  indefinite  noun  signifies  in  a  certain 
respect  one  thing,  just  as  "is  not  well"  is  not  a  verb,  but  an 
indefinite   verb.)     Still  without  a  verb  there  is    _,  ,   „ 

•  i  «.  ■'        .  /•       L,  •     »  Cf.  ch.  2,  and  3. 

neither  an  affirmation  nor  negation,  tor  "  is,  or 
"  will  be,"  or  "  was,"  or  "  is  going  to  be,"  and  so  forth,  are 
verbs,  from  what  has  been  already  laid  down,  since  in 
addition  to  something  else  they  signify  time.  Hence  the 
first  affirmation  and  negation  (will  be),  "man  is,"  "man  is 
not,"  afterwards  "non-man  is,"  "non-man  is  not."  Again, 
"  every  man  is,"  "  every  man  is  not,"  "  every  non-man  is," 
"every  non-man  is  not,"  and  the  same  reasoning  holds  in 
times  beyond  (the  present).4     But  when  "  is,"  is  additionally 

1  This  is  called  oppositio  tertii  adjacentis,  and  a  proposition  is  so  de- 
nominated -where  the  copula  is  separated  from  the  predicate ;  otherwise 
where  the  two  form  one  word,  as  "  He  walks,"  the  proposition  is  called 
secundi  adjacentis  ;  hitherto  the  latter  has  been  treated  of,  and  the  co- 
pula and  predicate  considered  equivalent  to  a  single  verb,  as  Xevkuv  (De 
Int.  ch.  2)  to  Xsvkov  tan.  I  have  followed  Taylor  in  finishing  the  sen- 
tence before  the  bracket. 

2  'At'uivvixov  vocat  to  aopiarov  ovo/ia  quod  ex  sequentibus  apparet, 
quamquam  to  dpwvvfiov  alium  sensum  habere  solet  apud  Arist.  Waitz. 
Vide  supra.  "  Something  of  something,"  means  of  which  something  is 
asserted. 

3  This  is  true  also  of  negation.  The  statement  has  already  been  made, 
ch.  8,  that  there  must  be  one  subject,  and  one  predicate.  Vide  Whately, 
b.  ii.  c.  2. 

4  Literally,  "  external  times,"  twv  ektoi;  fit  \pov(ov.  On  the  distinc- 
tion between  the  copula  and  the  third  per.  sing,  of  elfii,  as  predicating 
existence,  see  Pacius  de  Int.  c.  3,  and  Biese,  vol.  i.  p.  95. — Upon  the  pre- 
dicate having  the  negation  added  to  it  for  the  sake  of  obtaining  a  parti- 
cular affirmative  premise,  see  Whately.  b-  ii.  ch.  2  :  where  of  course  it  is 
added  to  the  subject,  as  in  the  text,  it  becomes  an  indefinite  subject,  to 
which  the  finite  is  stated  prior,  as  being  of  an  incomplex  nature,  and  by  this 
means  the  character  of  the  proposition  is  sometimes  changed,  and  the 


64  aristotle's  organon.  [chap,  x 

predicated  as  the  third  thing,  then  the  oppositions  are  enun- 
ciated doubly  ; l  I  say  for  instance,  "  a  man  is  just ; "  here  the 
word  "  is,"  I  say,  is  placed  as  a  third  thing,  whether  noun  or 
verb,  in  the  affirmation,  so  that  on  this  account,  these  will  be 
„  ,,.1.        ,     four,  of  which  two  will  subsist  with  respect  to 

2.  If  the  copula       „    '        .  .  ...  ,        r  „ 

be  added,  there  affirmation  and  negation,  according  to  the  order  ot 

MundaUons—  consequence,  as  privations,  but  two  will  not.2    But 

their  subsist-  I  say  that  the  word  "  is,"  will  be  added  to  "just "  or 

ence  exemp  i-  ^  « no^  just,"  *  so  that  also  negation  is  added,  where- 

*  Manornon-  fore  there  will  be  four.     We  shall  understand, 

man,  Waitz.  .  .        „  .' 

however,  what  is  said  from  the  under-written 
examples  :3  "  A  man  is  just,"  the  negation  of  this  is,  "  a  man 
isnotjust;"  "he  is  not  a  just  man,"  the  negative  of  this  is,  "he 
is  not  not  a  just  man,"  for  here  the  word  "is,"  and  "is  not," 
will  be  added  to  the  "just"  and  the  "not  just,"  wherefore 
An.  Pr.  46.     these  things,  as  we  have  shown  in  the  Analytics, 

are  thus  arranged.  The  same  thing  will  happen 
with°ttieirpe™'  ^  tne  affirmation  be  of  a  noun  taken  universally.4 
cuiiarity,  uni-     as  for  instance,  "every  man  is  just  ;"  of  this  the 

versals.  ,.         .      ,.  .     •       ,  „  ,, 

negation  is,  "  not  every  man  is  just,  "  every  man 
is  not  just,"  "not  every  man  is  not  just,"  except  that  it  does 
not  similarly  happen  that  those  which  are  diametrically  op- 
posed are  co- verified  ;5   sometimes,  however,  this  does  hap- 

subject  admits  an  affirmative.  Vide  Huyshe,  51,  and  the  translator's  note, 
AMrich's  Log.,  Oxford,  1843. 

1  That  is,  besides  the  two  terms,  (man)  subject,  and  (just)  predicate. 

*  The  enunciations  will  be  four  which  have  the  same  predicate,  and 
»n  a  certain  respect  the  same  subject.  Two  of  these,  he  says,  will  subsist 
with  respect  to  affirmation  and  negation  according  to  the  order  of  con- 
sequence, because  "  man  is  not  just,"  man  not  is  not  just,  are  referred  to 
J'  man  is  just,"  "  man  not  is  just,"  as  privations  are  referred  to  habits. 
By  the  word  negation  here,  he  does  not  mean  the  whole  proposition,  but 
the  words  "  not  is."     Farther  on  he  calls  "  not "  negative. 

3  'Ek  tH)v  v-iroyiypa.iip.ivwv.     Tabula  hoc  modo  disponenda  erit 


ovk  tanv  oil  SLiccuog  avOphnrog  "\~         ~p  ovk  sfsrt  oiicaiog  avOpajnog 


tan,  SiKaiog  avQpwTrog  — -^  "Etrriv  ov  Biicaiog  avOpunrog. 

Waitz. 
The  place  subsequently  referred  to  in  the  Analytics,  is  upon  the  opposition 
of  indefinites. 

4  That  is,  of  a  distributed  subject,  which  is  the  case  in  universal  pro- 
position.   Vide  Whately,  book  ii.  ch.  2,  sect.  2. 
4  Since  indefinites  are  compared  to  particulars,  in  contingent  matter 


CHAP.  X.]  ON    INTERPRETATION".  65 

pen,  these  two  therefore  are  opposed  to  each  other.  4  others  witi 
But  the  other  two  (are  opposed)  in  respect  to  an  indefinite 
"  non-man,"  as  to  a  certain  added  subject,  as  su  Ject' 
"non-man  is  just,"  "non-man  is  not  just,"  "the  non-just  is 
not  man,"  "the  not  non-just  is  not  man:"  there  are  not, 
however,  more  oppositions  than  these,  but  these  without 
those,  will  be  by  themselves,  as  using  the  noun,  "  non-man." 
In  those,  however,  wherein,  "  is,"  is  not  adapted, — as  in  "  he 
enjoys  health,"  and  "  he  walks," — here  it  produces  the  same 
when  thus  placed,  as  if  "is"  were  added;  as  "  every  man 
enjoys  health,"  "  every  man  does  not  enjoy  health,"  "  every 
non-man  enjoys  health,"  "every  non-man  does  not  enjoy 
health."  For  it  must  not  be  said,  "  not  every  man,"  but  the 
negation,  "not,"  must  be  added  to  "  man  ;"  for  "every"  does 
not  signify  universal,  but  that  (the  thing  is  taken)  universally.1 
This  is  however  evident,  from  "  a  man  enjoys  health,"  "  a  man 
does  not  enjoy  health,"  "  non-man  is  well,"  "  non-man  is  not 
well,"  these  differ  from  those,  in  not  being  universally  (taken).2 
Hence  "  every,"  or  "  no  one,"  signifies  nothing  else,  than  that 
affirmation  or  negation  is  of  a  noun  universally  (assumed) ; 
wherefore  it  is  necessary  to  add  other  things  of  the  same  kind.3 
But  because  the  contrary  negation  to  this,  "  every  animal 
is  just,"  is  that  which  signifies  that  "no  animal  is  just,"  it 
is  evident  that  these  will  never  be  either  true  at  the  same 
time,  nor  in  respect  to  the  same  subject,  but  the  opposites  to 
these  will  sometimes  be  so,  as  "not  every  animal  is  just," 
and  "some  animal  is  just."4  But  these  follow;  5  consequence 
the  one,  "no  man  is  just,"  follows  "every  man   of  the  negative 

opposite  enunciations  may  be  true.  Contraries  are  both  false  in  contin- 
gent matter,  never  both  true  ;  subcontraries  both  true  in  contingent  mat- 
ter, never  both  false  ;  contradictories  always  one  true,  another  false.  Vide 
scheme  of  opposition. 

1  "  Every,"  "  all,"  "  no,"  etc.,  are  called  universal  signs,  and  show 
that  the  subject  is  distributed ;  but  when  the  common  term  has  no  sign 
at  all,  the  indefinite  is  decided  by  the  propositional  matter,  i.  e.  is  uni- 
versal in  impossible,  aud  particular  in  contingent  matter.  Vide  the  com- 
mon Logics. 

2  The  enunciations,  "  man  is  well,"  "  man  is  not  well,"  differ  from 
"  every  man  is  well,"  "  every  man  is  not  well." 

3  That  is,  as  the  indefinite  is  made  indefinite  by  the  addition  of  nega- 
tion to  the  subject,  the  same  should  be  done  in  a  definite  enunciation,  as 
"  every  man  is  well,"  every  non-man  is  well,  rd  ovv  aWa  ra  avrd  ctl 
irpooTtOtvcu,  "  reliqua  ergo  eadem  oportet  (dicentem)  apponere."   Buhle 

*  These  are  the  particulars,  or  subcontraries. 

$ 


66  aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  x. 

upon  the  af-       is  not  just,"  but  the  opposite,  "  some  man  is  just." 
firmative,  and    f0nows  «  not  every  man  is  not  i  ust ,"  for  it  is  neces- 

sary  that  some  man  should  be  just.  In  the  case 
also  of  singulars,  it  is  evident  that  if  a  man  being  questioned 
denies  truly,  he  asserts  also  truly,  as,  "Is  Socrates  wise? 
No  ! "  Socrates  therefore  is  not  a  wise  man.  But  in  the  case 
of  universals,  what  is  similarly  asserted  is  not  true,  but  the 
negation  is  true,  as,  "  Is  every  man  wise  ?  No ! "  Every  man 

therefore  is  not  wise ;  for  this  is  false,  but  this, 
hvTMeitxevrr-      t(  not  every  man  then  is  wise,"  is  true,  and  this  is 

opposite,  but  that  is  contrary. 
Opposites,  however,  as  to  indefinite  nouns  and  verbs,  as  "  non- 
man  "  and  "non-just,"  may  seem  to  be  negations  without  a  noun 
and  verb,  but  they  are  not  so,  for  the  negation  must  always  of 
necessity  be  either  true  or  false,  but  he  who  says  "  non-man  " 
does  not  speak  more  truly  or  falsely,  but  rather  less,  than  he  who 

says  "  man,"  except  something  be  added.  Still  the 
nitenoWie-  assertion,  "every  non-man  is  just,"  does  not  sig- 
gitimate  enun-  njfy  fae  game  as  any  one  0f  those  (propositions),  nor 

the  opposite  to  this,  namely,  "  not  every  non-man 
is  just ;"  but  the  assertion,  "  every  one  not  just  is  not  a  man," 
means  the  same  with,  "  no  one  is  just  who  is  not  a  man." 

Nouns  and  verbs  indeed,  when  transposed,  have  the  same  sig- 
nification, as,  "  he  is  a  white  man,"  "  he  is  a  man  white,"  for 
unless  it  be  so,  there  will  be  many  negations  of  the  same  thing, 
but  it  has  been  shown  that  there  is  one  of  one ;  of  this,  "  he 
is  a  white  man,"  there  is  the  negation  "  he  is  not  a  white  man," 
and  of  the  other,  "  he  is  a  man  white,"  (except  this  be  the 
same  with  "  he  is  a  white  man,")  the  negation  will  either  be 
"  he  is  not,  not  a  man  white,"  or  "  he  is  not  a  man  white." 
7.  No  differ-  But  the  one  is  a  negation  of  this,  "  he  is  not  a 
ence  in  affirm-    man  white,"  and  the  other  of  this,  "  he  is  a  white 

ation  or  nega-  ..  ,      ,  '  ,  ..,  ,  ,•  e 

tion  produced     man    (so1  that  there  wdl  be  two  negations  ot  one 

1  This  parenthetical  sentence  is  omitted  by  Taylor,  but  given  by  Bek- 
ker,  Waitz,  Buhle,  and  Averrois  ;  the  last  gives  the  following  scheme  of 

Enunciationum  indefinitarum  dispositio. 

.    f  Affirmativa  simplex  Negativa  simplex         )  B 

\  Homo  est  Justus  Homo  non  est  Justus  J 

r  I  Negativa  infinita  Affirmativa  infinita      )  D 

(  Homo  non  est  non  Justus  Homo  est  non  Justus  J 

p  (  Negativa  privatoria  Affirmativa  privatoria  )  p 

\  Homo  non  est  injustus  Homo  est  injustus       ) 


CHAP.  XI.  |  ON    INTERPRETATION'.  67 

affirmation)  ;  wherefore  it  is  evident  that  when  a   by  transposi- 
noun  and  verb  are  transposed,  the  same  affirmation   tI0"' 
and  negation  result. 


Chap.  XL — Of  the  Composition  and  Division  of  Propositions. 

To  affirm,  and  deny,  one  thing  of  many,  or  many  (  0ne  thino, 

of  one,  is  not  one  affirmation  nor  one  negation,  cannot  be  said 

except  that  is  some  one  thing  which  is  manifested  lany nJi one, 

from  the  many  ;  I  mean  by  one,  not  if  one  name  b>' one  affirma- 

,  ,-,  •  •  r.  i  •  i       tIon  or  nega- 

be  given  to  many  things,  nor  it  jne  thing  result  tion.— Excep- 
from  them,  as  "man"  is  perhaps  "  animal,"  and  tlon' 
"biped,"  and  "mild,"  yet  one  thing  results  from  these  ;  but 
from  "  white"  and  "  man,"  and  "  to  walk,"  one  thing  does  not  re- 
sult, so  that  neither  if  a  person  affirm  one  certain  thing  of  these 
is  it  one  affirmation,  but  there  is  one  articulate  sound  indeed,1 
yet  many  affirmations,  nor  if  he  affirmed  these  things  of  one, 
(would  there  be  one  affirmation,)  but  in  like  manner,  many.  If, 
then,  dialectic  interrogation  be  the  seeking  of  an  answer,  either 
of  a  proposition,  or  of  either  part  of  a  contradiction,  (but  a 
proposition  is  a  part  of  one  contradiction,)  there  would  not  be 
one  answer  to  these,  for  neither  is  there  one  interrogation, 
not  even  if  it  be  true :  we  have,  however,  spoken  of  these  in 
the  Topics,  at  the  same  time  it  is  evident  that,   Topics,  vm.  7. 


What  is  it  ?  is  not  a  dialectic  interrogation,2  for  a   s°p'>-  .EL  . 

...  .  „  °  .  tf.  Prior  An. 


.  c.  6. 

A'rinr 

choice  should  be  given  from  the  interrogation  to   i.  i. 


He  divides  also  "universals"  and  "particulars"  after  the  same  manner. 
The  whole  treatise  he  distinguishes  into  two  books,  the  2nd  commencing 
with  this  chapter,  and  treating  of  indefinite  enunciations  generally.  The 
Greeks  resolved  it  into  five  sections  ;  Boethius,  sometimes  into  two,  and 
at  others  into  six  books ;  the  Latin  translators  generally,  into  two  books. 
These  differences,  in  the  earlier  commentators,  have  given  rise  to  much 
confusion  in  quotation,  amongst  their  successors. 

1  Or  (ptuvrj  fiia — una  vox.  Aristotle's  doctrine  in  the  Topics  differs 
from  that  of  Porphyry,  as  the  latter  does  from  Aldrich.  The  word 
Ka.Tt)y6pi}(ia,  occurrent  lower  down,  signifies  a  predicable — the  expres- 
sions categorematic  and  syncategorematic  are  not  Aristotelian,  but  are 
met  with  in  Michael  Psellus.  Cf.  Trendelenburg,  Elem.  sect.  9.  Waitz, 
vol.  i.  p.  267. 

2  On  the  nature  of  the  interrogation,  see  Whately  ii.  2,  1,  and  upon 
interrogational  fallacy,  book  iii.  sect.  9.  Si  quis  vero  quoerit  ita  ut  quod 
responderi  debeat  unum  quidem  sit,  sed  detinitione  data  exponendum, 
unum  quidem  est  quod  quaeritur  et  quod  respondetur,  quoestio  vero  dia- 

F  2 


68  Aristotle's  organox.  [chap,  xi 

irpo3.op.'<ru<rflai.   enunciate  this  or  that  part  of  the  contradiction ; 
Taylor.  ^ut  ^ie  interrogator  must  besides  define,  whether 

this  particular  thing,  or  not  this,  be  a  man. 

As,  however,  there  are  some  things  predicated 

as  composites,  so  that  there  is  one  whole  predicable, 
of  those  which  are  predicated  separately,  but  others  are  not  so, 
what  is  the  difference  ?  For  in  respect  of  "  man,"  we  may  truly 
and  separately  predicate  "animal " and  " biped,"  and  these  as  one 
thing  ;  also  "man"  and  "white,"  and  these  as  one  thing  ;  but 
not  if  he  is  "  a  shoemaker"  and  "  a  good  man,"  is  he  therefore 

also  a  good  shoemaker.  For  if,  because  each  of 
not  to  be  as-  these  is  true,  both,  conjointly,  should  be  of  neces- 
sumed,  as  con-   gjty   true,    many  absurdities   would   follow,    for 

junctively  true.  J  '  J     .  ' 

"  man  and  "  white  are  truly  predicated  ol  a 
man,  so  that  the  whole  together  may  be ; '  again,  if  the  thing 
"is  white,"  the  whole  conjointly  "is  white,"  wherefore,  it 
will  be  "  a  man  white,  white,"  even  to  infinity ;  again,  "  a 
musician  white  walking,"  and  these  frequently  involved  to 
infinity.  Once  more,  if  "  Socrates"  is  "  Socrates"  and  "man," 
"  Socrates"  is  also  "  Socrates  man,"  and  if  he  is  "man"  and 
"biped."  he  is  also  "man  biped  ;"  wherefore  it  is  evident,  if 
a  man  says  conjunctions  are  simply  produced,2  the  result  will 
be  that  he  will  utter  many  absurdities. 

Let  us  now  show  how  they  are  to  be  placed.  Of  things 
predicated,  and  of  those  of  which  it  happens  to  be  predi- 
cated, whatever  are  accidentally  enunciated,  either  in  respect 
of  the  same,  or  the  one  of  the  other,  these  will  not  be  one  ;  as 
"man  is  white,"  and  "a  musician;"  but  "whiteness"  and 

lectica,  quoniam  qtiaestione  dialectics  non  interrogator  quae  sit  hominis 
definitio,  sed  utrum  haec  sit  hominis  definitio,  an  non  sit.    Waitz. 

1  Since  "  man  "  and  "  white"  are  predicated  at  the  same  time,  and  the 
subject  may  be  said  to  be  "  a  white  man."  The  rule  is,  that  we  cannot 
use  a  separate  predicate  when  there  is  in  the  subject  any  thing  so  opposed 
to  a  portion  of  the  predicate,  as  to  cause  any  contradiction,  as  if  a  dead 
man  were  called  a  man.  If  there  is  any  contradiction  between  the  pre- 
dicate and  subject,  the  proposition  will  be  false,  yet  if  there  be  no  such 
contradiction,  it  does  not  follow  that  the  latter  is  always  true.  In  most 
cases,  however,  of  this  sort,  we  find  a  fourth  term  surreptitiously  intro- 
duced, by  the  ambiguity  of  the  copula. 

2  Tag  avfiTrXoKag  a.Tr\oJg  yivtaOai,  si  quis  simpliciter  dicat  com- 
plexiones  fieri.  Averrois.  Compare  Whately,  book  i.  and  ii.  ch.  5  ;  also 
book  iii.  sect.  9 ;  also  Hill's  Logic,  10S,  et  seq.,  and  observations  upon 
logical  division. 


CIIA.P.  XII.]  ON   INTERPRETATION.  69 

"  music"  are  not  one  tiling,  for  both  are  accidents  to  the  same 
thing.  Neither  if  it  be  true  to  call  what  is  white  musical, 
yet  at  the  same  time  will  "musical"  "white"  be  one  thing, 
for  what  is  "white"  is  "  musical  "  per  accidens,  so  that  "  white 
musical"  will  not  be  one  thing,  wherefore  neither 
is  a  man  said  to  be  "a  good  shoemaker"  singly,  simple  and™ 
but  also  "  a  biped  animal,"  because  these  are  not  |j°™£°snite  pre" 
predicated  of  him  per  accidens.  Moreover,  nei- 
ther are  such  things  which  are  inherent  in  another  (to  be 
added),  hence,  neither  is  "  whiteness "  (to  be  predicated) 
repeatedly,  nor  is  "a  man"  "a  man  animal,"  nor  (a  man) 
"  biped,"  since  both  animal  and  biped  are  inherent  in  man ; 
still  it  is  true  to  assert  it  singly  of  some  one,  as  that  "  a  cer- 
tain man  is  a  man,"  or  that  "  a  certain  white  man  is  a  white 
man,"  but  this  is  not  the  case  always.  But  when  some  op- 
position is  in  the  adjunct  which  a  contradiction  follows,  it  is 
not  true,  but  false,  as  to  call  a  dead  man  a  man,  but  when 
such  is  not  inherent,  it  is  true.  Or  when  something  (contra- 
dictory) is  inherent,  it  is  always  not  true ;  but  when  it  is  not 
inherent,  it  is  not  always  true,  as  "  Homer"  is  something,  "a 
poet,"  for  instance,  "is"  he  therefore,  or  "is"  he  not?  for 
"is"  is  predicated  of  Homer  accidentally,  since  "is"  is  predi- 
cated of  Homer  because  he  is  a  poet,  but  not  per  se  (or  essen- 
tially). Wherefore,  in  whatever  categories,  contrariety  is  not 
inherent,  if  definitions  are  asserted  instead  of  nouns,  and  are 
essentially  predicated,  and  not  accidentally,  of  these  a  parti- 
cular thing  may  be  truly  and  singly  asserted ;  but  non-being, 
because  it  is  a  matter  of  opinion,  cannot  truly  be  called  a 
certain  being,  for  the  opinion  of  it  is,  not  that  it  is,  but  that 
it  is  not. 

Chap.  XII. —  On  Modal  Proposition.1 

These  things  then  being  determined,  let  us  con-    i.  of  thenega- 
sider  how  the  affirmations,  and  negations  of  the   tions -7"~v  \mf 

.  -  .  .    ,  p  TOV  aval,  6i  0€- 

possible  and  impossible  to  be,  subsist  with  reter-   pwwe^., 
ence  to  each  other,  also  of  the  contingent  and  the 

1  Aristotle  here  enumerates  four  modes,  but  in  Anal.  Prior,  i.  2,  they 
are  reduced  to  two,  the  necessary  and  contingent.  See  St.  Hilaire's 
Translation.  The  Greek  commentators  have  multiplied  the  modes,  by 
allowing  any  adverb,  added  to  the  predicate,  or  adjective  qualifying  the 
Bubject  to  constitute  a  modal.     The  word  rpo7roe,  as  applied  to  the  modes 


70  aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  xir. 

non-contingent,  and  of  the  impossible  and  necessary,  since  this 
has  some  doubtful  points.  For  if  among  the  complex,  those 
contradictions  are  mutually  opposed,  which  are  arranged  ac- 
cording to  the  verb  "  to  be,"  and  "  not  to  be,"  (as  for  instance 
the  negation  "to  be  a  man,"  is  "not  to  be  man,"  not  this, 
"  to  be  not  a  man,"  and  the  negation  of  "  to  be  a  white  man  " 
is  "  not  to  be  a  white  man,"  and  not  this  "  to  be  not  a  white 
man,"  since  if  affirmation  or  negation  be  true  of  every  thing,  it 
will  be  true  to  say  "  that  wood  is  not  a  white  man,") — if  this  be 
so,  in  those  things  to  which  the  verb  "  to  be  "  is  not  added, 
that  which  is  asserted  instead  of  the  verb  "  to  be,"  will  pro- 
luce  the  same  thing.  For  example,  the  negation  of  "  a  man 
walks,"  will  not  be  "  non-man  walks,"  but,  "  a  man  does  not 
walk,"  for  there  is  no  difference  in  saying  that  "  a  man  walks," 
or  that  "  a  man  is  walking,"  so  that  if  this  is  every  where  the 
case,  the  negation  of  "  it  is  possible  to  be,"  will  be  "  it  is  pos- 
sible not  to  be,"  and  not  "  it  is  not  possible  to  be."  But  it 
appears  that  it  is  possible  for  the  same  thing  both  to  be,  and 
not  to  be,  for  every  thing  which  may  possibly  be  cut,  or  may 
possibly  walk,  may  also  possibly  not  be  cut,  and  not  walk,  and 

the  reason  is  that  every  thing  which  is  thus  pos- 
oiJLVw^f-  sible?  cloes  not  always  energize,1  so  that  negation 

will  also  belong  to  it,  for  that  which  is  capable 
of  walking,  may  not  walk,  and  the  visible  may  not  be  seen. 
Still  however  it  is  impossible  that  opposite  affirmations  and 
negations  should  be  true  of  the  same  thing,  wherefore  the  ne- 

of  propositions  and  of  syllogisms,  comes  from  the  Greek  commentators, 
but  is  not  Aristotelian.  (Ammonius  Schol.  p.  130,  a.  16.)  The  ad- 
mission of  modals  into  Logic,  has  been  strongly  advocated  and  opposed ; 
the  determination  of  the  implied  matter  of  a  pure  proposition  is  extra- 
logical  of  course,  but  respecting  the  expressed  matter  of  a  modal,  the 
reader  will  find  some  valuable  remarks  in  Mansel's  Logic.  The  authorities 
are,  on  one  side  of  the  question  Sir  W.  Hamilton,  on  the  other  Kant 
and  St.  Hilaire.  A  modal  is  reducible  to  a  pure  categorical,  by  uniting 
the  modal  word  to  the  predicate,  or  to  the  subject  when  the  mode  only 
expresses  the  nature  of  the  matter  of  the  proposition,  e.  g.  a  fish  neces- 
sarily lives  in  the  water,  i.  e.  all  fish  live  in  the  water.  Though  the  man- 
ner of  connexion  between  the  extremes  is  expressed  in  a  modal,  yet  it 
does  not  thereby  test  the  quantity  of  the  proposition,  as  there  are  uni- 
versal and  particulars  in  each  mode.  On  the  distinction  of  propositional 
matter,  see  Sir.  W.  Hamilton,  Ed.  Rev.  No.  115,  p.  217.  Also  the  com- 
mentary of  Ammonius,  de  Int.  7,  (Scholia,  p.  115,  a.  14). 

1   "  Non  semper  in  actu  est.''     Averrois.    Cf.  Metap.  lib.  ii.  4,  and  books 
"  and  8 ;  also  Physics,  lib.  ii. 


CHAP.  XII.]  ON    INTERPRETATION.  71 

gation  of  "it  is  possible  to  be,"  is  not  "it  is  possible  not  to 
be."  Now  it  results  from  this  that  we  either  at  the  same 
time  affirm  and  deny  the  same  thing  of  the  same,  or  that  the 
affirmations  and  negations  are  not  made  according  to  the  ad- 
ditions, "  to  be  "  or  "  not  to  be  ; l "  if  therefore,  that,  be  im- 
possible, this,  will  be  to  be  taken,  wherefore  the  negation  of 
"it  is  possible  to  be,"  is  "it  is  not  possible  to  be," 
(but*  not  it  is  possible  not  to  be).  Now  there  is  *B?k™'*]ed  by 
the  same  reasoning  also  about  the  being  contingent, 
for  the  negation  of  this  is,  not  to  be  contingent,  and  in  like 
manner  as  to  the  rest,  for  example  the  necessary  and  impossible, 
since  as  in  those  it  happens  that,  "  to  be,"  and,  "  not  to  be,"  are 
additions,  but  "whiteness"  and  "man"  are  subjects,  so  here 
"  to  be  "  and  "not  to  be,"  become  as  subjects,  but  "  to  be  possi- 
ble," and  "  to  be  contingent,"  are  additions  which  determine  the 
true  and  false  in  the  (enunciations)  "to  be  possible"  and  "to 
be  not  possible,"  similarly  as  in  those,  "  to  be,"  and  "  not  to  be."  2 
But  of  "it  is  possible  not  to  be,"  the  negation  is  not,  "it  is  not 
possible  to  be,"  but  "it  is  not  possible  not  to  be,"  and  of  "  it  is 
possible  to  be," the  negation  is  not,  "it  is  possible  not  to  be,"  but, 
"it  is  not  possible  to  be  ;"  wherefore,  "it  is  possible  to  be,"  and, 
"it  is  possible  not  to  be,"  will  appear  to  follow  each  other  ;  for  it 
is  the  same  thing,  "  to  be  possible  to  be,"  and  "not  to  be,"  since 
such  things  are  not  contradictories  of  each  other,  namely,  "it  is 
possible  to  be,"  and,  "  it  is  possible  not  to  be."     But  "  it  is  pos- 

1  Sequitur  enim  hinc  aut  idem  vere  simul  affirmari  et  negari  de  eodeni 
aut  non  secundum  apposita  quatenus  ea,  sunt  et  non  sunt,  fieri  afiirma- 
tiones  et  negationes.  Si  ergo  illud  fieri  nequit  (ut  negatio  propositionis 
modalem  negativam  effieiat)  hoc  (tit  negatio  modi  efficiat  modalem  nega- 
tivam)  eligendum  fuerit.     Buhle. 

3  Vide  Huyshe's  Logic,  p.  50.  As  regards  modality,  judgments  accord- 
ing to  Kant  are  problematical,  assertorial,  and  apodeictieal.  The  first  are 
accompanied  by  a  consciousness  of  the  bare  possibility  of  the  judgment; 
the  second  by  a  consciousness  of  its  reality  ;  the  third  by  a  consciousness 
of  its  necessity.  Modality  is  thus  dependent  on  the  manner  in  which  a 
certain  relation  between  two  concepts  is  maintained,  and  may  vary  ac- 
cording to  the  state  of  different  minds,  the  given  concepts,  and  conse- 
quently the  matter  of  the  judgment,  remaining  unaltered.  Mansel's  Prol. 
Log.,  and  Appendix,  note  G.  The  real  state  of  the  case  appears  to  be  that, 
in  the  endeavour  to  combine  psychological  variation  with  logical  distinct- 
ness, philosophers  have  sacrificed  the  proper  office  of  the  latter.  As  far 
as  proposition  is  concerned,  modals  may  be  tuined  at  once  into  pure  ea- 
tegoricals,  in  fact,  they  affect  not  the  relation  between  the  terms,  but  sim- 
ply the  subject  or  predicate,  in  other  words,  the  terms  themselves  alone. 


72  Aristotle's  organon.  [chap.  xm. 

sible  to  be,"  and  "  it  is  not  possible  to  be,"  are  never  true  of 
the  same  thing  at  the  same  time,  for  they  are  opposed,  neither 
at  least  are,  "  it  is  possible  not  to  be,"  and  "  it  is  not  possible 
not  to  be,"  ever  true  at  the  same  time  of  the  same  thing.  Like- 
wise of,  "it  is  necessary  to  be,"  the  negation  is  not,  "it  is 
necessary  not  to  be,"  but  this,  "  it  is  not  necessary  to  be,"  and 
of,  "it  is  necessary  not  to  be,"  (the  negation)  is  this,  "it  is 
not  necessary  not  to  be."  Again,  of,  "it  is  impossible  to  be," 
the  negation  is  not  "it  is  impossible  not  to  be,"  but  "it  is  not 
impossible  to  be,"  and  of,  "  it  is  impossible  not  to  be,"  (the 
negation)  is,  "  it  is  not  impossible  not  to  be."  In  fact,  uni- 
versally, as  we  have  said,  "to  be"  and  "not  to  be,"  we  must 
2.  The  elvat  necessarily  regard  as  subjects,  but  those  things 
and  uh  eivat  to    which  produce  affirmation  and  negation  we  must 

be  considered  r  » 

as  subjects,  connect  with  "to  be  and  "not  to  be  :  we  ought 
Tfflrlnltion  and  a^so  to  consider  these  as  opposite  affirmations  and 
negation  is  to  negations  ;  possible,  impossible,  contingent,  non- 
contingent,  impossible,  not  impossible,  necessary, 
not  necessary,  true,  not  true. 

Chap.  XIII.     Of  the  Sequences  of  Modal  Propositions. 

The  consequences  are  rightly  placed  thus  :  "  it 
thod^fdis^os-  happens  to  be,"  follows,  "  it  is  possible  to  be,"  and 
coL^uences.  tms  reciprocates  witn  that ;  also,  "  it  is  not  impos- 
sible to  be"  and  "it  is  not  necessary  to  be."  But, 
"  it  is  not  necessary  not  to  be,"  and,  "it '  is  not  impossible  not  to 
be;"  follow,  "it  is  possible  not  to  be,"  and,  "it  may  happen 
not  to  be  ; "  and,  "  it  is  necessary  not  to  be,"  and,  "  it  is  im- 
possible to  be,"  follow,  "  it  is  not  possible  to  be,"  and,  "  it  does 
not  happen  to  be;"  but,  "it  is  necessary  to  be,"  and  also, 
"it  is  impossible  not  to  be,"  follow,  "it  is  not  possible  not  to 
be,"  and,  "  it  is  not  contingent  not  to  be  : "  what  we  say  how- 
ever may  be  seen  from  the  following  description  : 

1  3 

It  is  possible  to  be  It  is  not  possible  to  be 

It  may  happen  to  be  It  may  not  happen  to  be 

1  Bekker,  Buhle,  and  Waitz  read  this  clause  differently :  as  all  are, 
however,  agreed  in  the  scheme  given,  I  have  reconciled  their  variation 
by  a  reference  to  that.     Taylor  appears  to  have  done  the  same. 


CIIAP.  XIII.]  ON    INTERPRETATION.  73 

It  is  not  impossible  to  be  It  is  impossible  to  be 

It  is  not  necessary  to  be.  It  is  necessary  not  to  be. 

2  4 

It  is  possible  not  to  be  It  is  not  possible  not  to  be 

It  may  happen  not  to  be  It  may  happen  not  to  be 
It  is  not  impossible  not  to  be      It  is  impossible  not  to  be 

It  is  not  necessary  not  to  be.  It  is  necessary  to  be. 

Therefore  the  impossible,  and  the  not  impossi-    i. 


to  aoi'i 


aoovaroV' 


ble,  follow  contradictorily  the  contingent,  and  the  liai  °'"t  d : 
possible,  and  the  non-contingent,  and  the  not  »*.  reciproce. 
possible,  and  vice  versa  ;  *  for  the  negation  of  the 
impossible,  namely,  "  it  is  not  impossible  to  be,"  follows,  "  it  is 
possible  to  be,"  but  affirmation  follows  negation,  for,  "it  is  im- 
possible to  be  "  follows  "  it  is  not  possible  to  be,"  since  "  it  is 
impossible  to  be,"  is  affirmation,  but,  "  it  is  not  impossible  to 
be,"  is  negation. 

Let  us  next  see  how  it  is  with  necessary  matter,  now  it  is 
evident  that  it  does  not  subsist  thus,  but  contraries  follow, 
and  contradictories  (are  placed)  separately,1  for,  "  it  is  not  ne- 
cessary to  be,"  is  not  the  negation  of  "  it  is  ne-   „    , , 

„     .  ,  Mil  2.  to  avayxaioi', 

cessary  not  to  be,  since  both,  may  possibly  be  true  its  peculiarity, 
of  the  same  thing,  as  that  which  necessarily,  is  not,  ana^roof.6*50" 
need  not  of  necessity,  be.  But  the  reason  why  the 
necessary  follows  not,  in  like  manner,  other  propositions,  is 
that  the  impossible  being  enunciated  contrarily  to  the  ne- 
cessary, signifies  the  same  thing  ;  for  what  it  is  impossible 
should  exist,  must  not  of  necessity  be,  but  not  be,  and  what  is 
impossible  should  not  be,  this  must  of  necessity  be ;  so  that 
if  these  similarly  follow  the  possible  and  the  not  possible, 
these  (do  so)  in  a  contrary  mode,2  since  the  necessary  and  the 
impossible  do  not  signify  the  same  thing,  but,  as  we  have  said, 

1  Contrarias  eas  appellat,  quum  propterea  quod  non  est  aliud  nomen, 
quod  its  melius  conveniat,  turn  maxime  propter  locos,  quos  occupant  in 
tabula  quam  adscripsit  •  nam  in  hac  e£  tvavrlaq  collocate  sunt  ovk  dvay- 
kcuov  tlvai  et  avay.  /xtj  tlvai  Waitz.  In  the  table  given  above  the  two 
former  in  each  column  are  contraries  to  the  two  former  in  the  opposite ; 
and  the  two  latter  in  each  are  contrary  sequences  from  the  two  former. 
Necessity,  according  to  Aristotle,  (Ethics,  ch.  iii.,)  was  either  absolute 
(airXwg),  or  hypothetical  (t£  vTroOkuewg),  the  former  immutable,  the  lat- 
ter only  conditional.    See  also  Metap.  lib.  iv. 

*  Namely,  "  it  is  necessary  and  it  is  net  necessary." 


74  Aristotle's  organon.  [chap,  xiii, 

Buhie  and  v^ce  vers^-  Or  is  it  impossible  that  the  contra- 
Averrois  omit  dictories  of  the  necessary  should  be  thus  disposed  ? 
equeaion.  g^  what,  "is  necessary  to  be"  is  "possible  to 
be,"  since  if  not,  negation  would  follow,  as  it  is  necessary  eithei 
to  affirm  or  deny,  so  that,  if  it  is  not  possible  to  be,  it  is  im- 
possible to  be,  wherefore  it  would  be  impossible  for  that  to 
be,  which  necessarily  is,  which  is  absurd,  but  the  enunciation, 
"it  is  not  impossible  to  be"  follows  the  other,  "it  is  possible 
to  be,"  which  again  is  followed  by,  "  it  is  not  necessary  to 
be,"  whence  it  happens  that  what  necessarily  exists  does  not 
necessarily  exist,  which  is  absurd.  But  again  neither  does, 
"it  is  necessary  to  be"  follow  "it  is  possible  to  be,"  nor 
does  the  proposition,  "  it  is  necessary  not  to  be,"  for  to  that, 
both,  may  occur,  but  whichever  of  these  is  true,1  those2  will 
be  no  longer  true,  for  at  one  and  the  same  time,  it  is  possible 
to  be,  and  not  to  be,  but  if  it  is  necessary  either  to  be  or  not 
to  be,  both,  will  not  be  possible.  It  remains  therefore,  that 
"it  is  not  necessary  not  to  be,"  follows  "  it  is  possible  to  be  ;" 
for  this3  is  also  true  in  respect  of  what  is  necessary  to  be, 
since  this  becomes  the  contradiction  of  that  proposition  which 
follows,  viz.  "it  is  not  possible  to  be;"  as  "it  is  impossible 
to  be,"  and  "  it  is  necessary  not  to  be,"  follow  that,  of  which  the 
negation  is,  "  it  is  not  necessary  not  to  be."  Wherefore  these 
contradictions  follow  according  to  the  above-mentioned  mode, 
and  nothing  absurd  results,  when  they  are  thus  disposed.4 

Still  it  may  be  doubted  whether  "  it  is  possible 
diileiuy™  °tfoa  to  be,"  follows  "  it  is  necessary  to  be,"  for  if  it 
the  above,  by     does  not  follow,  the  contradiction  will  be  conse- 

the  distinction  .        '    .  ..  ,  .      „         ,   .„ 

between  ration-  quent,  namely,  "it  is  not  possible  to  be,  and  it  a 
ai  potenUainy "  man  should  deny  this  to  be  a  contradiction,  it  will 
be  necessary  to  call,  "  it  is  possible  not  to  be,"  a 
contradiction,  both  which  are  false  in  respect  of  necessary 
matter.  Nay,  on  the  contrary,  it  appears  to  be  possible  that  the 
same  thing  should  "  be  cut"  and  "  not  be  cut,"  should  "  be"  and 
"not  be,"  so  that  what  necessarily  "is,"  may  happen  "not  to  be," 
which  is  false.  Nevertheless  it  is  evident  that  not  every  thing 
which  can  "  be,"  and  can  "  walk,"  is  capable  also  of  the  op- 
posites,  for  in  some  cases  this  is  not  true.     In  the  first  place, 

1  That  is,  it  is  necessary  to  be,  and  it  is  necessary  not  to  be. 

7  It  is  possible  to  be,  and  it  is  possible  not  to  be. 

*  It  is  not  necessary  not  to  be.  *  As  above. 


CHAP.  XIII.]  ON    INTERPRETATION.  75 

in  those  things  which  are  potent  irrationally,1  as 
fire  is  calorific,  and  has  irrational  power  ;  rational  ^^"Jfx°7°" 
powers  then  are  those  of  many  things,  and  of 
the  contraries  ;  but  not  all  irrational  powers,  for,  as  we 
have  said,  fire  cannot  heat,  and  not  heat,  nor  such  other 
things  as  always  energize.  Yet  even  some  irrational  powers 
can  at  the  same  time  receive  opposites ;  but  this  has  been 
stated  by  us,  because  not  every  power  is  susceptible  of  con- 
traries, not  even  such  as  are  predicated,  according  to  the 
same  species.  Moreover,  some  powers  are  equivocal,  for  the 
possible  is  not  predicated,  simply  ;  but  one  thing  is  (called  so), 
because  it  is  true,  as  being  in  an  energy,  as  it  is  possible  for  a 
man  to  walk,  because  he  walks,  and  in  short,  a  thing  is  pos- 
sible to  be,  because  that  is  already  in  energy  which  is  said  to 
be  possible ;  on  the  other  hand,  another  thing  (is  said  to  be 
possible),  because  it  may  be  in  energy ;  as  it  is  possible  to 
walk,  because  a  man  may  walk.  Now  this  power  exists  in 
movable  natures  only,  but  that  in  immovable  ;  but  with  re- 
spect to  both,  it  is  true  to  say,  that  it  is  not  impossible  to 
walk  or  to  be,  and  that  a  man  is  now  walking  and  energizing, 
and  has  the  power  to  walk,  hence  it  is  not  true2  to  predicate 
that  which  is  thus  possible,  in  respect  of  necessary  matter, 
simply,  but  the  other  is  true.  Wherefore  since  the  universal 
follows  the  particular,  to  be  able  to  be,  but  not  all  ability,  fol- 
lows that  which  is  of  necessity,  and  indeed  the  3  The  iyayKaX. 
necessary  and  the  non-necessary  may  perhaps  be   ov  km  uh  a*, 

1  Non  secundum  rationem  possibilia.  Buhle.  "  Non  secundum  ratio- 
nem  possunt."  Averrois.  Compare  Metaph.  lib.  ii.  and  iv.  and  viii.  In 
the  last  place,  the  same  distinction  between  rational  and  irrational  powers 
is  maintained ;  the  reader  will  find  also  that  the  whole  of  the  8th  chapter 
turns  on  the  difference  between  SwdfiiQ  and  ivepyeia.  Briefly,  the  former 
is  (as  here)  simple  potentiality ;  the  latter,  that  active  state,  in  which 
potentiality  may  be.  Aristotle  places  the  ivepytia,  and  properly,  ante- 
cedent to  the  dvi'a/iic.  Vide  also  Ethics,  book  i.  ch.  2.  Aw(i/j«j  con- 
sidered as  faculties  were  five,  of  which  vegetables  possessed  one,  brutes 
four,  and  man  all.  Compare  Aristot.  de  Animu.  The  resistance  given, 
has  respect  to  the  potentiality  of  the  will,  which  of  course  is  excluded 
from  irrational  subjects,  hence  they  are,  in  a  sense,  unsusceptible  of  con- 
traries ;  man's  will,  being  potential,  has  power  to  restrict  his  Zvvapuq, 
or  place  them  in  tvtpytiq,  but  irrational  subjects  have  no  potential  will, 
hence  the  difference. 

2  It  is  only  truly  asserted  of  what  is  hypothetically  necessary,  because 
a  thing  must  of  necessity  be,  when  it  will  be,  though  it  will  not  neces- 
sarily be. 


76  ARISTOTLE'S    ORGANON.  [CHAP.  XIT. 

are  the  &px4  the  principle  of  the  existence,  or  of  the  non-exist- 
*«>™*  «»«"• '"  ence  of  all  things,  and  we  should  consider  other 
things  as  consequent  upon  these.1  Hence  from 
what  we  have  stated,  it  is  clear  that  whatever  exists  of  necessity, 
is  in  energy,  so  that  if  eternal  natures  are  prior  in  existence, 
4.  The  to  if,  energy  also  is  prior  to  power,  and  some  things,  as 
faAyiwhv.  icar"  the  first  substances,  are  energies  without  power, 
Priority.  but  others  with  power,  namely,  those  which  are 

prior  by  nature,  but  posterior  in  time  :  lastly,  there  are  some 
which  are  never  energies,  but  are  capacities  only. 

Chap.  XIV.     Of  Contrary  Propositions.2 

1.  Those  opin-    But  whether  is  affirmation  contrary  to  negation, 
ions  are  con-      or  affirmation  to  affirmation  ?  and  is  the  sentence 

1  The  following  order  will  explain : 

1  3 

It  is  necessary  to  be  It  is  not  necessary  to  be 

It  is  not  possible  not  to  be  It  is  possible  not  to  be 

It  may  not  happen  not  to  be  It  may  happen  not  to  be 

It  is  impossible  not  to  be.  It  is  impossible  not  to  be. 

2  4 

It  is  necessary  not  to  be  It  is  not  necessary  not  to  be 

It  is  not  possible  to  be  It  is  possible  to  be 

It  may  not  happen  to  be  It  may  happen  to  be 

It  is  impossible  to  be.  It  is  not  impossible  to  be. 

Waitz  observes  that  he  does  not  consider  the  Trpwrjj  ovaia  here  as  in  the 
Categories,  but  as  in  the  Metaphysics.  Vide  Metap.  b.  iii.  4,  6,  etc.,  also 
Physics,  lib.  ii.  and  De  Anima,  i.  1,  2,  and  ii.  1,  2.  Ed.  Trendelenburg. 
The  learned  note  of  Ammonius,  too  long  to  insert,  tends  to  show  no 
more  than  what  can  be  gleaned  by  the  student  from  a  reference  to  the 
places  quoted,  namely,  that  with  Aristotle,  energy  is  prior  to  capacity, 
and  that  the  necessary  being  invariably  the  same  in  subsistence,  can  only 
be  predicated  of  things  which  are  always  in  energy :  this  conclusion 
being  syllogistically  educed,  he  proceeds  to  evolve  the  contingents  and 
consequences,  placing  form  in  energy,  matter  in  capacity.  In  the  Meta. 
12th  book,  he  calls  the  gods— essences  in  energy.  Composites  are  those 
which  participate  of  matter,  and  either  may  or  may  not  retain  form  :  thus 
beings  are,  first,  energies  simple  and  immutable,  next,  those  which  are 
mutable,  yet  connected  with  energy,  others,  which  precede  energy  as  to 
time,  but  do  not  always  obtain  it,  lastly,  others  which  subsist  as  to  capa- 
city alone,  and  are  not  naturally  adapted  to  energy.  Vide  Ammonius  in 
librum  de  Interpretatione. 

2  This  chapter  is  not  given  separately  in  the  text,  by  Waitz:    with 
Ammonius  it  forms  the  fifth  section  of  the  treatise.   He  considers  it  eithei 


CIIAI*.  XIV. J 


ON    INTERPRETATION.  77 


which  says,  "every  man  is  just,"  contrary  to  the   trary wMch  are 
one,  "no  man  is  iust,"  or  the  sentence  "every   of  contrary 

.     .  „  ,,  ■  l_  »  -c  rt   l       matter,  and  the 

man  is  just,    to,  "every  man  is  unjust,    as     Ual-   prepositional 
lias  is  just,"  "  Callias  is  not  just,"  "  Callias  is  un-  r^f^ 
just," — which  of  these   are  contraries  ?    For  if  the  contrariety 
things  in  the  voice,  follow  those  which  exist  in   of  °Pimon- 
the  intellect,1  but  there  the  opinion  of  a  contrary  is  contrary,  ' 
as  for  instance,   that   "every  man  is  just,"  is  contrary  to, 
"  every  man  is  unjust,"  it  is  necessary  that  affirmations  also 
in  the  voice  should  subsist  in  the  same  manner,  but  if  there, 
the  opinion  of  a  contrary  be  not  contrary,  neither  will  affirm- 
ation be  contrary  to  affirmation,   but  the  before-named  ne- 
gation.    Hence  it  must  be  considered  what  false  opinion  is 
contrary  to  the  true  opinion,  whether  that  of  negation  or  that 
which  opines  it  to  be  the  contrary.     I  mean  in  this  way, 
there  is  a  certain  true  opinion  of  good  that  it  is  good,  but  an- 
other false  opinion  that  it  is  not  good,  lastly,  a  third,  that  it  is 
evil,  which  of  these  therefore  is  contrary  to  the  true  opinion  ? 
and  if  there  is  one,  according  to  which  is  it  contrary  ?  If  then 
a  man  should  fancy  contrary  opinions  to  be  defined  by  this, 
that  they  are  of  contraries,  it  would  be  erroneous,  for  of  good 
that  it  is  good,  and  of  evil  that  it  is  evil,  there  is  perhaps  the 
same  opinion,  and  it  is  true  whether  there  be  many  (opinions) 
or  one  :  but  these  are  contraries,  yet  not  from  their  being  of 
contraries  are  they  contraries,  but  rather  from  their  subsist- 
ing in  a  contrary  manner.2  If  then  there  is  an  opinion  of  good 
that  it  is  good,  but  another  that  it  is  not  good,  and  there  is 
also  something  else,  which  is  neither  inherent,   nor  can  be, 
in  good,  we  cannot  admit  any  contrary  of  the  rest,  neither 

as  spuriously  introduced  by  some  one  posterior  to  Aristotle,  or  written  by 
him  to  exercise  the  reader's  judgment  upon  what  has  been  said,  as  in  the 
Categories  he  contends  that  what  is  sensible  is  prior  to  sense,  explaining 
the  system  of  relation  generally  in  his  Physical  Auscultation. 

1  Vide  supra,  ch.  i. ;  also  Ethics,  book  vi.  ch.  1  and  2.  As  Waitz  ob- 
serves, he  seems  to  refer  to  the  same  subject  in  the  Metaphysics,  where  he 
takes  for  granted  that  ivavria  kari  86%a  SoKy  r)  rrje  avriipcMTtwQ,  and  again 
in  the  Topics.  Waitz,  363.  Vide  also  Whately,  book  ii.  ch.  2,  3,  and 
Huyshe,  sect.  4  :  whose  remarks  will  fully  explain  this  chapter.  The 
example,  Callias  is  just— is  unjust,  is  in  fact  a  contradiction.  (Vide  De 
Interpreiatione,  ch.  7.) 

2  fiaWov  T(p  tvavriwg,  in  a  form  of  logical  contrariety.  On  the  three- 
fold division  of  good,  by  the  Pythagoreans  and  Peripatetics,  see  Cic. 
Acad.  i.  5 ;  Tusc.  v.  85.  Ethics,  book  i.  8. 


78  Aristotle's  organon.  [citap.  xrv. 

such  opinions  as  imagine  the  non-inherent  to  be  inherent,  nor 
the  inherent  to  be  non-inherent,  (for  both  are  infinite,1  both 
as  many  as  imagine  the  non-inherent  to  be  inherent,  and  the 
inherent  to  be  non-inherent)  ;  but  in  those  things  in  which  there 
is  deception,  (therein  we  admit  contraries,)  and  these  are  from 
which  there  are  generations ;  generations  however  are  from 
opposltes,  wherefore  deceptions  also.  If  then  good  is  good 
and  not  evil,  and  the  one  is  essential,  but  the  other  accidental 
— (for  it  is  accidental  to  it  not  to  be  evil)  and  of  every  thing 
the  opinion  is  more  true  and  false  which  is  essential,  if  the 
true  (be  assumed) — the  opinion  that  good  is  not  good,  is 
false  in  respect  of  that  which  is  essentially  inherent,  but 
the  opinion  that  it  is  evil  is  false  of  that  which  is  from  acci- 
dent, so  that  the  opinion  of  the  negation  of  good  would  be 
more  false  than  the  opinion  of  the  contrary.  He  is  however 
especially  deceived  about  every  thing  who  holds  a  contrary 
opinion,  for  contraries  belong  to  things  which  are  the  most 
diverse  about  the  same  thing.  If  then  one  of  these  is  con- 
trary, but  the  opinion  of  the  negation  is  more  contrary,  it 
is  evident  that  this  itself  will  be  (truly)  contrary ;  but  the 
opinion  that  the  good  is  evil  is  complex,  for  it  is  necessary 
perhaps,  that  the  same  man  should  suppose  (good)  not  good. 
Once  more,  if  it  is  requisite  for  the  like  to  occur  in  other  things, 
it  may  seem  to  have  been  well  said  in  this  case  also ;  for  the 
(opposition)  of  negation  is  either  every  where  or  no  where  ; 
but  whatever  things  have  no  contraries,  of  these,  the  opposite 
to  the  true  opinion  is  false,  as  he  is  mistaken  who  fancies  "  a 
man  "  "  not  a  man,"  if  then  these  (negations)  are  contrary  the 
other  (opinions)  also,  of  negation,  are.  Besides,  it  is  the  same 
as  to  the  opinion  of  good  that  it  is  good,  and  of  what  is  not 
good,  that  it  is  not  good ;  and  also  the  opinion  of  good,  that  it 
is  not  good,  and  of  what  is  not  good  that  it  is  good ;  to  the 
opinion  then  of  the  not  good  that  it  is  not  good,  which  is  true, 
2.  Nature  of  what  will  be  the  contrary  ?  Certainly  not  that 
contrariety  be-    -which  says  that  it  is  evil,  since  it  may  at  one 

tween  affirma-  J  .  » 

tion  and  nega-  and  the  same  time  be  true ;  but  truth  is  never 
tion"  contrary  to  truth,  for  whatever  is  not  good  is  evil, 

so  that  it  will  happen  that  these  opinions,  shall  be  at  one  and 
the  same  time,  true.  Nor  again  will  that  (opinion)  that  it  is  not 

1  This  parenthesis  is  omitted  by  Taylor.    I  follow  the  reading  of  Buhle 
and  Waitz. 


CHAP.  XIV. J  ON    INTERPRETATION.  79 

evil,  be  (the  contrary),  for  that  is  also  true,  and  these  may  exist 
at  the  same  time,  wherefore  (the  opinion)  of  what  is  not  good, 
that  it  is  good,  remains  as  a  contrary  to  the  opinion  of  what  is 
not  good,  that  it  is  not  good,  and  this  will  be  false,  so  that 
the  opinion  of  good  that  it  is  not  good,  will  be  the  contrary 
to  that  of  what  is  good,  that  it  is  good.  That  there  will  be  no 
difference  though  we  should  propose  universal  affirmation  is 
evident,  for  universal  negation  will  be  the  contrary  ;  as  for  in- 
stance, to  the  opinion  which  supposes  every  thing  good  to  be 
good,  that  nothing  of  good  things  is  good  (will  be  the  contrary 
opinion),  for  the  opinion  of  good  that  it  is  good,  if  good  be 
universal,  is  the  same  with  that  which  opines  that  whatever 
is  good  is  good,  and  this  differs  in  no  respect  from  the  opinion 
that  every  thing  which  is  good  is  good,  and  the  like  takes  place 
as  to  that  which  is  not  good.  So  that  if  this  be  the  case  in 
opinion,  and  affirmations  and  negations  in  the  voice  are  S)'m- 
bols  of  (conceptions)  in  the  soul,  it  is  clear  that  the  universal 
negation  which  is  about  the  same  thing,  is  contrary  to  affirm- 
ation. For  instance,  to  "  every  thing  good  is  good,"  or  that 
"every  man  is  good,"  (the  negation  is  contrary,)  that 
"  nothing  or  no  man  is  good  ;"  but  this,  that  "  not  every  thing, 
or  not  every  man,"  (is  good,  is  opposed)  contradictorily.  It 
is  however  evident,  that  true  opinion  can  neither  possibly  be 
contrary  to  true  opinion,  nor  true  negation  (to  true  negation), 
for  those  are  contraries  which  subsist  about  op-   _  „ 

r       8.  Contraries 

posites  ;  but  about  the  same  things  the  same  may  cannot  co-exist 
be  verified,  but  contraries  cannot  possibly  be  in-  uua  fc" T<fJ  avl't' 
herent  in  the  same  thing,  at  one  and  the  same  time.1 

1  Vide  the  canones  oppositarum.    Aldrich.     Also  notes  upon  the  7th 
chap,  de  Interpret. 


80  aristotle's  organon.  [book 


THE  PKIOR  ANALYTICS.1 

BOOK  I. 

Chap.  I. — Of  Proposition,  Term,  Syllogism,  audits  Elements. 

i.  Purport  of  It  is  first  requisite  to  say  what  is  the  subject, 
the8 attainment  concerning  which,  and  why,  the  present  treatise 
of  demonstra-  is  undertaken,  namely,  that  it  is  concerning  de- 
monstration, and  for  the  sake  of  demonstrative 
science ;  we  must  afterwards  define,  what  is  a  proposition, 
what  a  term,  and  what  a  syllogism,  also  what  kind  of  syllo- 
gism is  perfect,  and  what  imperfect;  lastly,  what  it  is  for 
a  thing  to  be,  or  not  to  be,  in  a  certain  whole,  and  what 
we  say  it  is  to  be  predicated  of  every  thing,  or  of  nothing 
(of  a  class). 

2.  Definition  of  A  proposition  then  is  a  sentence  which  affirms  or 
(irpoTa™)  pro-    denies  something  of  something,2  and  this  is  uni- 

position.     It  is  ,  .  °.  .     n       °.  T     , 

either,  versal,  or  particular,  or  indefinite  ;  1  denominate 

versfi°Xo",uni"  universal,  the  being  present3  with  all  or  none; 
2.  huepet,  par-  particular,  the  being  present  with  something,  or 
3?or^ii6punov,  n°t  with  something,  or  not  with  every  thing  ; 
indefinite.  but  the  indefinite  the  being  present  or  not  being 
present,  without  the  universal  or  particular  (sign) ;  as  for 
example,  that  there  is  the  same  science  of  contraries,  or  that 

1  Aristotle  herein  analyzes  syllogism  and  demonstration  into  their  prin- 
ciples ;  the  names  Prior  and  Posterior  were  given  to  these  treatises  in 
the  time  of  Galen,  but  it  is  remarkable,  that  when  Aristotle  cites  them, 
he  denominates  the  former,  "  Concerning  Syllogism,"  and  the  latter 
"  Concerning  Demonstration."  Upon  the  subject  of  title,  compare  St. 
Hilaire,  Memoire,  vol.  i.  p.  42,  with  Waitz,  vol.  i.  p.  367  ;  and  for  general 
elucidation  of  the  treatise  itself,  much  information  has  been  derived  from 
the  valuable  commentary  of  Pacius. 

8  Oratio  indicativa,  etc.,  Aldrich,  "  Oratio  enunciativa,"  Boethius.  The 
latter's  definition  is  the  better. 

3  The  word  vTrapxtw,  inesse,  has  given  ample  scope  for  the  exercise  of 
logical  contention :  Taylor  objects  to  translating  it,  the  being  inherent, 
and  points  out  an  anomaly  arising  from  Pacius'  use  of  it  in  this  way, 
in  the  next  chapter.  He  asserts  that  the  real  Aristotelian  sense  is 
"  being  present  with.*'  For  the  account  of  the  word,  see  note,  p.  53. 


CHAP.  I.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  81 

pleasure   is    not    good.      But   a    demonstrative   „  _._ 

to  3.  Difference 

proposition  differs  from  a  dialectic  in  this,  that   between  the 
the  demonstrative  is  an  assumption  of  one  part  of  f™°£**™*™}e 
the  contradiction,  for  a  demonstrator  does  not  in-   ana  the  3.aA«- 
terrogate,  but  assume,  but  the  dialectic  is  an  in- 
terrogation of  contradiction.1    As  regards  however  forming  a 
syllogism  from  either  proposition,  there  will  be  no  difference 
between  one  and  the  other,  since  he  who  demonstrates  and 
he  who  interrogates  syllogize,  assuming  that  something  is  or 
is  not  present  with   something.       Wherefore   a 
syllogistic  proposition  will  be  simply  an  affirma-   tic  proposition 
tion  or  negation  of  something  concerning  some- 
thing, after  the  above-mentioned  mode  :  it  is  however  demon- 
strative if  it  be  true,  and  assumed  through  hypo- 
theses from  the  beginning,2  and  the  dialectic  pro-   s{rJt^vedemon 
position  is  to  him  who  inquires  an  interrogation 
of  contradiction,  but  to  him  who  syllogizes,  an  assumption 
of  what  is  seen  and  probable,  as  we  have  shown  in  the  Topics. 
What  therefore  a  proposition  is,  and  wherein  the  syllogistic 
demonstrative  and  dialectic  differ,  will  be  shown  accurately 

1  The  oldest  Greek  commentator,  Alexander  Aphrodisiensis,  speaks  of 
the  Xoyitcr)  (cat  uvWoyiaTtKr)  TrpayfiaTiia  as  containing  under  it,  airo- 
SttKriKt),  StaXtKTiKt],  Trnpaarticr],  and  aocpiariKt].    Schol.  p.  149,  a.  19. 

2  These  are  d^nofiara,  the  truth  of  which  are  self-evident.  Waitz. 
They  correspond  to  the  Koivai  ivvotai  of  the  mathematicians.  The  place 
referred  to  is  the  1st  book  of  the  Topics.  As  assumption  by  the  name  of 
hypothesis  forms  one  of  the  Aristotelian  apxai,  or  principles  of  science,  we 
annex  the  following  table  of  the  latter  from  Mansel's  Appendix. 

'Apxcu 

I 
Koivai  (iK  u>v) Iciai  {irtpi  b) 

I  I 

a^idifiara  vifftig 

(original  premises) 


opiafioi  vTroQkaiiQ 

Definitions.  assumptions  of  the 

real,  of  the  subjects,  existence  of  the  subjects,  as 

nominal,  of  the  attributes.  a  necessary  condition 

to  their  definition. 
(N.  B.     The  attributes  are  not 
assumed,  but  proved  to  exist 
in  their  subjects.) 
0 


82  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

in  the  following  treatises,  but  for  our  present  requirements 

what  has  now  been  determined  by  us  may  per- 

6  Definition  of  h         suffice.     Again,  I  call  that  a  "  term,"  into 

a  term — apos.  i  .  V         .  ,  . 

which  a  proposition  is  resolved,  as  for  instance, 
the  predicate  and  that  of  which  it  is  predicated,  whether  to  be 
or  not  to  be  is  added  or  separated.     ^Lastly,  a 
Byiiogismfa        syllogism  is   a  sentence  in  which  certain  things 
being   laid  down,   something  else  different  from 
the  premises  necessarily  results,  in  consequence  of  their  ex- 
istence.1^ I  say  that,    "in  consequence  of  their  existence," 
something  results  through  them,  but  though  something  happens 
through  them,  there  is  no  need  of  any  external  term  in  order 
to  the  existence  of  the  necessary  (consequence). 
either  perfect,     Wherefore  I  call  a  perfect  syllogism  that  which 
zf  areAncf'        requires  nothing  else,  beyond  (the  premises)  as- 
sumed, for  the  necessary  (consequence)  to  appear : 
but  an  imperfect  syllogism,  that  which  requires  besides,  one 
or  more  things,  which  are  necessary,  through  the  supposed 
terms,  but  have  not  been  assumed  through  propositions.2  But 
for  one  thing  to  be  in  the  whole  of  another,  and  for  one  thing 
to  be  predicated  of  the  whole  of  another,  are  the  same  thing, 
„  „  c  ...         and  we  say  it  is  predicated  of  the  whole,  when  no- 

8.  Definition  J  l  '        . 

of  predication     thing  can  be  assumed  of  the  subject,  of  which  the 
nulio""1  et         other  may  not  be  asserted,  and  as  regards  being 
predicated  of  nothing,  in  like  manner.3 

1  Vide  Aldrich.  Aristotle's  definition  is  translated  by  Aulus  Gellius,  xv. 
26.  Oratio  in  qua,  consensis  quibusdam  et  concessis  aliud  quid,  quam 
qua?  Concessa  sunt,  per  ea,  quae  concessa  sunt  necessario  conficitur. 
On  the  subject  of  the  syllogism  being  a  petitio  principii,  vide  Mansel's 
Logic,  Appendix  D. 

8  Cf.  Aquinas  Opusc.  47.  de  Syll.  cap.  viii.  Scotus,  lib.  i.  Anal. 
Prior,  Quaest.  xxii.  seqq.  Occam,  Log.  p.  3,  cap.  6.  The  direct  and  in- 
direct syllogisms  of  the  Schoolmen  must  not  be  confounded  with  the  per- 
fect and  imperfect  of  Aristotle  :  an  indirect  syllogism  has  the  minor  term 
the  predicate,  and  the  major  the  subject,  of  the  conclusion. 

3  That  is,  when  nothing  can  be  assumed  of  the  subject  of  which  the 
other  can  be  predicated.  With  Aristotle  the  "  dictum  de  omni  et  nullo," 
is  the  principle  of  all  syllogism.  Vide  Whately,  b.  i.  sect.  4.  See  also  the 
same  principle,  Categor.  3. 


CHAP.  II.]  THE    PRIOR   A-NALYTIC  S.  83 


Chap.  II. — On  the  Conversion  of  Propositions. 

Since  every  proposition  is  either  of  that  which 
is  present  (simply),  or  is  present  necessarily  or  converse. 
contingently,  and  of  these  some  are  affirmative,   ^onveislon 
but  others  negative,  according  to  each  appellation  ;   in  e,  univer- 
again,sinceof  affirmative  and  negative  propositions   sa  y' 
some  are  universal,  others  particular,  and  others  indefinite,  it 
is  necessary  that  the  universal  negative  proposition  of  what 
is  present  should  be  converted  in  its  terms  ;  for  instance,  if 
"  no  pleasure  is  good,"  "  neither  will  any  good  be  pleasure." 
But  an  affirmative  proposition  we  must  of  neces-   2  A  and  j  (0 
sity  convert  not  universally,  but  particularly,1  as   be  converted 
if  "all  pleasure  is  good,"  it  is  also  necessary  that  par 
"a  certain  good  should  be  pleasure;"  but  of  particular  pro- 
positions, we  must  convert  the  affirmative  proposition  parti- 
cularly, since  if  "  a  certain  pleasure  is  good,"  so  also  "  will  a 
certain  good  be  pleasure ;"  a  negative  proposition  however 
need  not  be  thus  converted,  since  it  does  not  follow,    3  Conversion 
if  "  man  "  is  not  present  with  "  a  certain  animal,"   of  o  unneces- 
that  animal  also  is  not  present  with  a  certain  man. 

Let  then  first  the  proposition  A  B  be  an  universal  nega- 
tive ;  if  A  is  present  with  no  B,  neither  will  B  be  present 
with  any  A,  for  if  it  should  be  present  with  some  A,  for  ex- 
ample with  C,  it  will  not  be  true,  that  A  is  present  with  no 
B,  since  C  is  something  of  B.     If,  again,  A  is  pre-    .  „        , 

•  i  n    -n        -ii    i         i  •  i      4-  Examples. 

sent  with  every  B,  B  will  be  also  present  with 
some  A,  for  if  with  no  A,  neither  will  A  be  present  with  any 
B,  but  it  was  supposed  to  be  present  with  every  B.     In  a 
similar  manner  also  if  the  proposition  be  particular,  for  if  A 

1  Aristotle's  account  of  conversion  differs  from  that  of  Aldrich,  since  he 
divides  conversion  into  universal  and  particular,  having  respect  to  the  qua- 
lity of  the  proposition  after  conversion.  'AttXi)  avncrpo^r;  is  mentioned 
by  Philoponus  Scholia.  On  the  conversion  per  accidens,  of  the  logicians, 
see  Whately,  b.  ii.  sect.  4.  Boethius  uses  the  expressions  generalis  and 
per  accidens.  Whately's  term,  conversion  by  limitation,  is  far  better. 
The  example  in  the  text  is  worked  out  more  shortly  by  Theophrastus  and 
Eudemus.  It  is  to  be  noticed  that,  having  in  Inter,  ch.  12,  spoken  of  four 
modes,  he  here  reduces  them  to  two  Vide  St.  Hilaire's  Translation, 
Preface,  p.  66. 

g  2 


Pi  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

be  present  with  some  B,  B  must  also  necessarily  be  present 
with  some  A,  for  if  it  were  present  with  none,  neither  would 
A  be  present  with  any  B,  but  if  A  is  not  present  with  some 
B,  B  need  not  be  present  with  some  A,  for  example,  if  B  is 
"  animal,"  but  A,  "  man,"  for  man  is  not  present  with  "  every 
animal,"  but  "  animal "  is  present  with  "  every  man." 

Chap.  III. —  On  the  Conversion  of  Modal  Propositions} 

l  Rule  for  The  same  system  will  hold  good  in  necessary  pro- 
modai  conver-    positions,  for  an  universal  negative  is  universally 

sion  the  same  ,.,  ,       ,  .,1  /v.  r.  ... 

as  for  pure  pro-  convertible,  but  either  affirmative  proposition  par- 
positions.   Ex-  ticularlv ;  for  if  it  is  necessary  that  A  should  be 

ample  of  the  "       .  -n      ■      •         i  t  -r-» 

necessary  mo-  present  with  no  B,  it  is  also  necessary  that  B 
lal'  should  be  present  with  no  A,  for  if  it  should  hap- 

pen to  be  present  with  any,  A  also  might  happen  to  be  pre- 
sent with  some  B.  But  if  A  is  of  necessity  present  with 
every  or  with  some  certain  B,  B  is  also  necessarily  present 
with  some  certain  A ;  for  if  it  were  not  necessarily,  neither 
would  A  of  necessity  be  present  with  some  certain  B :  a 
particular  negative  however  is  not  converted,  for  the  reason 
we  have  before  assigned. 

In  contingent  propositions,  (since  contingency  is  mul- 
tifariously predicated,  for  we  call  the  necessary,  and  the  not 
necessary,  and  the  possible,  contingent,)  in  all  affirmatives, 
conversion  will  occur  in  a  similar  manner,  for  if  A  is  con- 
tingent to  every  or  to  some  certain  B,  B  may  also  be  con- 
tingent to  some  A ;    for  if  it  were  to  none,  neither  would 

A  be  to  any  B,  for  this  has  been  shown  before. 

The  like  however  does  not  occur  in  negative 
propositions,  but  such  things  as  are  called  contingent  either 
from  their  being  necessarily  not  present,  or  from  their  being 
not  necessarily  present,  (are  converted)  similarly  (with  the 

1  Modality  is  not  altogether  excluded  from  Logic ;  but  is  admitted  by 
Aristotle,  only  when,  being  expressed  in  a  proposition,  it  necessitates  un- 
der certain  conditions  a  corresponding  modification  of  consequence. 
Logic  has  nothing  to  do  with  deciding  the  truth  or  falsity  of  proposition, 
per  se,  necessarily  or  contingently ;  it  only  ascertains  the  necessary  infer- 
ence of  conclusion  from  premises  according  to  certain  canons.  Vide 
some  admirable  remarks  by  Sir  W.  Hamilton  on  this  subject.  Psellus 
and  Petrus  Hispanus  are  both  extra-logical  in  their  consideration  of 
matter. 


CHAP.  IV.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  85 

former);    e.  g.  if  a  man  should  say,  that   it  is  2  of  the  con- 
contingent,   for  "a  man,'  not  to  be  "a  horse,"   tingent,  with 
or  for  "  whiteness  "  to  be  present  with  no  "  gar-   examp  e* 
ment."    For  of  these,  the  one,  is  necessarily  not  present,  but 
the  other,  is  not  necessarily,  present ;   and  the  proposition  is 
similarly  convertible,  for  if  it  be  contingent  to  no  "  man  "  to 
be  "  a  horse,"  it  also  concurs  with  no  "  horse  "  to  be  "  a  man," 
and  if  "  whiteness  "  happens  to  no  "  garment,"  a  "  garment  " 
also  happens  to  no  "  whiteness ; "  for  if  it  did  happen  to  any, 
"whiteness"  will  also  necessarily  happen  to  "a  certain  gar- 
ment," and  this  has  been  shown  before,  and  in    (Ch  2 , 
like  manner  with  respect  to  the  particular  negative 

-r>    j       i  ,,•  11    ?  3.  Of  things 

proposition.     But  whatever  things  are  called  con-   calied  contin- 
tingent  as  being  for  the  most  part  and  from  their  sent,  with  the 

o  o  x  .  differences  m 

nature,  (after  which  manner  we  define  the  contin-   conversion  oe- 
gent,)  will  not  subsist  similarly  in  negative  conver-   tween  E  and  °- 
sions,  for  an  universal  negative  proposition  is  not  converted,  but 
a  particular  one  is,  this  however  will  be  evident  when  we  speak 
of  the  contingent.     At  present,  in  addition  to  what  we  have 
said,  let  thus  much  be  manifest,  that  to  happen  to  nothing,  or 
not  to  be  present  with  any  thing,  has  an  affirma-   ,  Cf  ch  12  de 
tive  figure,*  for  "  it  is  contingent,"  is  similarly  ar-   interpreta- 
ranged  with  "it  is,"  and  "it  is"  always  and  entirely 
produces  affirmation  in  whatever  it  is  attributed  to,  e.  g.  "it 
is  not  good,"  or,  "  it  is  not  white,"  or  in  short,  "  it  is  not  this 
thing."     This  will  however  be  shown  in  what  follows,  but 
as  regards  conversions,  these  will  coincide  with  the  rest. 

Chap.  IV. —  Of  Syllogism,  and  of  the  first  Figure. 

These  things  being  determined,  let  us  now  de-    i.  syllogism 
scribe  bv  what,  when,  and  how,  every  syllogism  is   being  mo,Tf, 

J  '  '    „  '  i       n    T  universal  than 

produced,  and  let  us  afterwards  speak  ol  demon-   demonstration 
stration,  for  we  must  speak  of  syllogism  prior  to   ed^to^ature 
demonstration,   because   syllogism  is   more   uni-   and  constmc- 
versah  since,  indeed,  demonstration  is  a  certain 
syllogism,  but  not  every  syllogism  is  demonstration. 

When,  then,  three  terms  so  subsist,  with  reference  to  each 
other,  as  that  the  last  is  in  the  whole  of  the  middle,  and  the  mid- 
dle either  is,  or  is  not,  in  the  whole  of  the  first,  then  it  is  neces- 
sary that  there  should  be  a  perfect  syllogism  of  the  extremes. 


86  Aristotle's  oroanon.  [book  i. 

.  But  I  call  that  the  middle,1  which  is  itself  in  an- 

«'m«Vo«,  and  of  other,  whilst  another  is  in  it,2  and  which  also  be- 
tfPs-ii0egXismPle  comes  tne  middle  by  position,3  but  the  extreme4 
that  which  is  itself  in  another,  and  in  which  an- 
other also  is.5  For  if  A  is  predicated  of  every  B,  and  B  of 
every  C,  A  must  necessarily  be  predicated  of  every  C,  for  it 
has  been  before  shown,  how  we  predicate  "  of  every  ; "  so  also 
if  A  is  predicated  of  no  B,  but  B  is  predicated  of  every  C,  A 
will  not  be  predicated  of  any  C.     But  if  the  first  is  in  every 

1  That  is,  in  the  first  figure,  because  the  middle  is  piaced  otherwise  in 
the  second  and  third  figures. 

2  That  is,  in  the  first  figure ;  the  middle  is  the  subject  of  the  major  pre- 
mise, and  predicate  of  the  minor. 

3  That  is,  the  middle  is  placed  between  the  extremes.  Aristotle,  in 
his  figures,  regards  rather  the  extension  of  the  middle,  than  its  position 
in  the  two  premises.  Vide  Trendelenburg,  Elem.  sect.  28.  Waitz,  Anal. 
Pr.  23. 

4  The  majus  extremum,  to  fitl^ov  olkdov,  is  called  also  to  Tzpu>Tov. 
An.  Pr.  book  i.  ch.  31 ;  the  minus,  to  iXcittov,  also  to  taxarov-  An. 
Pr.  book  ii.  ch.  8.    Cf.  Aldrich,  cap.  iii.  sect.  3. 

5  The  minor  extreme  is  the  subject  of  the  middle  in  the  minor  pre- 
mise ;  and  the  major  extreme  is  the  predicate  of  the  middle  in  the  major 
premise. 

Ex.  1.  Every  man  is  an  animal  Every  man  is  an  animal 

No  horse  is  a  man  No  stone  is  a  man 

Every  horse  is  an  animal.  No  stone  is  an  animal. 

Ex.  2.  No  line  is  science  No  line  is  science 

No  medicine  is  a  line  No  unity  is  a  line 

Every  medicine  is  science.         No  unity  is  science. 


Ex. 


Some  Habit  {  »  not }  good  Some  habit  { |J  not }  good 

All  prudence  is  a  habit  All  ignorance  is  a  habit 

All  prudence  is  good.  No  ignorance  is  good. 


l£x.  4.  Some  horse  j .        .  J  white  Some  horse  |  •„  n  t }  white 

No  swan  is  a  horse  No  crow  is  a  horse 

Every  swan  is  white.  No  crow  is  white. 

Kx  5.  Every  man  is  an  animal  Every  man  is  an  animal 

Something  white  (i.  e.  a  swan)  Something  white  (i.  e.  snow)  is  not 

is  not  a  man  a  man 

Every  swan  is  an  animal.  No  snow  is  an  animal. 

Ex.  6.  No  man  is  inanimate  No  man  is  inanimate 

Something  white  (i.'  e.  snow)  Something  white  (i.  e.  a  swan)  id 

is  not  a  man  not  a  man 

A 11  snow  is  inanimate.  No  swan  is  inanimate. 


CHAP.  IV.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  87 

middle,  but  the  middle  is  in  no  last,  there  is  not  a  syllogism 
of  the  extremes,  for  nothing  necessarily  results  from  the  ex- 
istence of  these,  since  the  first  happens  to  be  present  with 
every,  and  with  no  extreme ;  so  that  neither  a  particular  nor 
universal  (conclusion)  necessarily  results,  and  nothing  neces- 
sary resulting,  there  will  not  be  through  these  a  syllogism. 
Let  the  terms  of  being  present  universally,  be  "  animal,"  "man," 
"  horse,"  and  let  the  terms  of  being  present  with  no  one  be 
"animal,"  "man,"  "stone."*    Since,  then,  neither 

.  -ii  -in  i  .Lxample  (1.) 

the  first  term  is  present  with  the  middle,  nor  the 
middle  with  any  extreme,  there  will  not  thus  be  a  syllogism. 
Let  the  terms  of  being  present,  be  "  science,"  "  line,"  "  medi- 
cine," but  of  not  being  present,  "  science,"  "  line,"    f  Ex      ,e  (2 
<(unity;"f  the  terms  then  being  universal,  it  is 
manifest  in  this  figure,  when  there  will  and  when  there  will 
not  be  a  syllogism,  also  that  when  there  is  a  syllogism,  it  is 
necessary  that  the  terms  should  subsist,  as  we  have  said,  and 
that  if  they  do  thus  subsist  there  will  evidently  be  a  syllogism 
But  if  one  of  the  terms  be  universal  and  the  other  particu 
Iar,  in  relation  to  the  other,  when  the  universal  is  joined  to  the 
major  extreme,  whether  affirmative  or  negative,  but  the  par- 
ticular to  the  minor  affirmative,  there  must  necessarily  be  a 
perfect  syllogism,  but  when  the  (universal)  is  joined  to  the 
minor,  or  the  terms  are  arranged  in  some  other  way,  a  (syl- 
logism) is  impossible.     I  call  the  major  extreme 

i     ^    •  i_-    l    xi  •!,,      •  j    ,i  •  xi  3.  Definition  of 

that  in  which  the  middle  is,  and  the  minor  that   T(,  ucr£0„,  and 
which  is  under  the  middle.     For  let  A  be  present   7°  <^aTTO" 
with  every  B,  but  B  with  some  C,  if  then  to  be 
predicated  "  of  every  "  is  what  has  been  asserted  from  the  first, 
A  must  necessarily  be  present  with  some  C,  and  if  A  is  pre- 
sent with  no  B,  but  B  with  some  C,  A  must  necessarily  not 
be  present  with  some  C,  for  what  we  mean  by  the  being  predi- 
cated of  no  one  has  been  defined,  so  that  there  will  be  a  perfect 
syllogism.     In  like  manner,  if  B,  C,  being  affirm-   4  syllogistic 
ative,  be  indefinite,  for  there  will  be  the  same  syl-   ratio  the  same 
logism,  both  of  the  indefinite,  and  of  that  which   as  for  thes- 
is assumed  as  a  particular.  Ocular. 

If  indeed  to  the  minor  extreme  an  universal  af-  5-  No  syllogism 
urinative  or  negative  be  added,  there  will  not  be  Univeisai,°bute 
a  syllogism,  whether  the  indefinite,  or  particular,    the  major  par- 

J       &         >  ,  .  .         x  ticular,  or  m- 

affinns  or  denies,  e.  g.  11  A  is  or  is  not  present   definite. 


88  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i, 

with  some  B,  but  B  is  present  to  every  C  ;  let  the  terms 
of  affirmation  be  "good,"  "habit,"  "prudence,"  and  those 
•Example  (3.)   of    negation>    "good,"    "habit,"    "  ignorance." * 

Again,   if  B  is  present  Avith   no  C,   but  A  is 

present  or  is  not  present  with  some  B,  or  not  with  every 

B  ;  neither  thus  will  there  be  a  syllogism  ;  let  the  terms  of 

.   being  present  with  every  (individual)  be  "  white,"  f 

"horse,"  "swan;"  but  those  of  being  present 
with  no  one,  be  "  white,"  "  horse,"  "  crow."     The  same  also 

may  be  taken  if  A,  B  be  indefinite.  Neither  will 
the  major  is"  there  be  a  syllogism,  when  to  the  major  extreme 
AorE.butthe   the   universal  affirmative  or  negative  is  added; 

minor  O.  ,  ,  ,  °  .       . 

but  to  the  minor,  a  particular  negative,  whether 
it  be  indefinitely  or  particularly  taken,  e.  g.  if  A  is  present 
with  every  B ;  but  B  is  not  present  with  some,  or  not  with 
every  C,  for  to  what  the  middle  is  not  present,  to  this,  both  to 
every,  and  to  none,  the  first  will  be  consequent.  For  let  the 
terms,  "animal,"  "man,"  "white,"  be  supposed,  afterwards 
from  among  those  white  things,  of  which  man  is  not  predicated, 
let  "swan"  and  "snow"  be  taken ;  hence  "animal"  is  predi- 
cated of  every  individual  of  the  one,  but  of  no  individual  of  the 
,  ,_ ,   other,  wherefore  there  will  not  be  a  syllogism. t 

%  Example  (5.)      .        . *     .  -n  i 

Again,  let  A  be  present  with  no  B,  but  B  not  be 
present  with  some  C,  let  the  terms  also  be  "  inanimate," 
"  man,"  "  white,"  then  let  "  swan"  and  "  snow"  be  taken  from 
those  white  things,  of  which  man  is  not  predicated,  for  inani- 
mate is  predicated  of  every  individual  of  the  one,  but  of  no 
.  Exam  j  .  .   individual  of  the  other.  §     Once  more,  since  it  is 

indefinite  for  B  not  to  be  present  with  some  C, 
(for  it  is  truly  asserted,  that  it  is  not  present  with  some  C, 
whether  it  is  present  with  none,  or  not  with  every  C,)  such 
terms  being  taken,  so  as  to  be  present  with  none,  there  will 
be  no  syllogism  (and  this  has  been  declared  before).  Where- 
fore it  is  evident,  that  when  the  terms  are  thus,  there  will  not 
be  a  syllogism,  since  if  one  could  be,  there  could  be  also  one 
in  these,  and  in  like  manner  it  may  be  shown,  if  even  an  uni- 
,  XT      .  versal  negative  be  taken.     Nor  will  there  by  any 

7.  Nor  when  °  .  -  .  /        J 

both  are  parti-  means  be  a  syllogism,  it  both  particular  mter- 
cuiar,  etc.         vajg  i  ke  pre(jiCated  either  as  affirmative  or  nega- 

1  Propositions.    "  Propositio  ipsa  vocatur  passim  ab  Aristotele,  '  inter- 


CHAP.  V.J  THE   PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  89 

tive,  or  the  one  affirmative  and  the  other  negative,  or  the  one 
indefinite,  or  the  other  definite,  or  both  indefinite  ;  but  let  the 
common  terms  of  all  be  "animal,"  "white,"  "man,"  „  Example  (7 } 
"animal,"  "white,"  "stone."* 

From  what  has  been  said,  then,  it  is  evident,  that  if  there 
be  a  particular  syllogism  in  this  figure,  the  terms  must  ne- 
cessarily be  as  we  have  said,  and  that  if  the  terms  be  thus, 
there  will  necessarily  be  a  syllogism,  but  by  no    8  2x-ua  wpS. 
means  if  thev  are  otherwise.    It  is  also  clear,  that  ™>-   The  first 

*  .         ,  .       „  s%         ,    n         figure  com- 

all  the  syllogisms  in  this  figure  are  perfect,1  tor  Piete,andcom- 
all  are  perfected  through  the  first  assumptions  ;  and   £[aeshs*"d0sf  *" 
that  all  problems  are  demonstrated  by  this  figure,   firmation  and 
for  by  t'his,  to  be  present  with  all,  and  with  none,   nesatlon- 
and  with  some,  and  not  with  some,  (are  proved,)  and  such  I 
call  the  first  figure.2 


o 


Chap.  V Of  the  second  Figure. 

When  the  same  (middle  term)  is  present  with  every  1 ,  jXnu».  b„ 
individual,  (of  the  one,)  but  with  none,  (of  the  ^^ 
other,)  or  is  present  to  every  or  to  none  of  each,   position  of  the 

vallum,' '  Siaor^a,'  quoniam  duobus  extremis  terminis  includitur,  eorum- 
que  intervallutn  efficit."     Buhle. 

Ex.  7.  Something  white  I J*  nQt  ]  an  Something  white  j  ^  no(.  |  an  ani- 

animal  mal 

Some  man  {  |j  not }  white  Some  stone  {  J  nQt }  white 

Every  man  is  an  animal.  No  stone  is  an  animal. 

1  For  the  special  and  general  rules  of  syllogism,  see  the  common 
Logics.  It  is  sufficient  to  observe  here,  that  the  Aristotelian  dictum  is 
directly  applicable  only  to  the  first  figure,  which  is  therefore  the  type  of 
all  syllogisms,  and  that  the  special  rules,  as  laid  down  by  Petrus  Hispa- 
nus,  may  all  be  found  in  this  and  the  following  chapters. 

2  On  the  term  7rpo/3\//f<ara,  compare  Alexander  Schol.  p.  150,  b.  xl. 
with  this  place,  and  also  with  Topics,  i.  4.  Schol.  p.  256,  a.  14,  here,  it 
is  used  as  lr\roi\itva,  or  "  qusestiones,"  upon  which  vide  Aldrich,  cap.  3. 
The  term  oxwara,  is  employed,  as  Pacius  thinks,  by  Aristotle,  because 
of  his  illustration  of  syllogisms  by  geometrical  figures.  Vide  Waitz,  vol. 
i.  384.  The  invention  of  the  fourth  figure  (disowned  by  Aristotle)  is 
attributed  by  Averrois  to  Galen.  TpoVoc,  or  mood,  is  not  used  in  Aid- 
rich's  sense  by  Aristotle,  except,  perhaps,  in  the  28th  chapter  of  this 
book.  In  the  same  meaning,  Aristotle  uses  7rrt5<Tic  in  An.  i.  26.  Upon 
the  perfect  and  imperfect  moods,  vide  Whately  and  Aldrich, (Mansel'z  Ed.) 


0: 


-       7    -      -  1_     -    --  =■:  >"    :•-  :c 

v-rx  m  M :  i»n:  M  "was  •  nyy i n  ni  A  »e  pre- 

;     —•••:     -    >"  -_    :*    :----—-    z~:    I. 

__~  liar  ieenpnweo  Defies.      AgmiiF  Mh  p  !■■*  ■iflt 

■ 

—  w  l  ...,.  .."  i_-:    :   — Z 


i 


_ 


"_j  - 


- 


; 


-__   - 


I    =  " 


:  i  - 


~.~    _"_    r_ 


-     Z       -        .      r--    .'..  - 




_ 


!    -.1 


■  -"    : 


:_-- 


c:  ^         "  r^z   -zr.i  aSjlLtzz:  9i 


i  ?dbffl«,  Let  t&e  lens  of 

■  ;.--  -  - 

■  syTiflgiwa,  wheat  31  is  rerefaer  pc 

•     :  . ■    "  .-    •  - 

--    ~"  :::-•;:  .    : 

^armr.-.  '      -     -     "- 

H-:.t  .:  -    -    -      -    .-    -    -  .   -  -.. 


-7- 

' 

iio£am"  X. 

— ^ 

■ .      -  . 

- 


::  -  _  - 
it'ifae 

:-    i  -     -  -  7"  "    .     .  _    :~      -  .  "    "  ■  _  . "     -    -        .  ■'—     ■    —  ■ .  -    ■  - 
§1  T-li  r—  _:.      7   :  .: -  : :---  "      -     -  "    r 


:-     ;:";-:_:.  2-  — L  ' -.  ~  :-.  -.-  ::       "     i  .   -  -   "  :"  . 
:-      :  — -""  — :_  i 

A  I  —  _  i  < 

■  ■     :  -  -  ~  -  - 

.:  .-     -  -   .  -     -  '    -     '- 

Ex.  - 

V ; 


-- 


92  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

M  must  necessarily  be  present  with  every  0,  but  it  was  sup- 
posed not  to  be  present  with  a  certain  0,  and  if  M  is  present 
with  every  N,  and  not  with  every  0,  there  will  be  a  syllogism, 
that  N  is  not  present  with  every  O,  and  the  demonstration 
will  be  the  same.     But  if  M  is  predicated  of  every  O,  but  not 
of  every  N,  there  will  not  be  a  syllogism ;  let  the  terms  of 
presence  be  "  animal,"  "  substance,"  "  crow,"  and  of  absence 
"  animal,"  "white,"  "crow  ;"*  neither  will  there 
be  a  syllogism  when  M  is  predicated  of  no  0,  but  of 
a  certain  N,  let  the  terms  of  presence  be  "animal,"  "substance," 
.  ,„ .    "  stone,"  but  of  absence,  "  animal,"  "  substance," 

t  Example  (4.)  .  ,,  . 

"  science,   j 
When  therefore  universal  is  opposed  to  particular,  we  have 
declared  when  there  will,  and  when  there  will  not,  be  a  syllogism  ; 

but  when  the  propositions  are  of  the  same  quality,1 
4.  if  both  pre-  as  both  being  negative  or  affirmative,  there  will  not 
Tz^quafitT  by  any  means  be  a  syllogism.  For  first,  let  them  be 
no  syllogism      negative,  and  let  the  universal  belong  to  the  major 

extreme,  as  let  M  be  present  with  no  N,  and  not  be 
present  with  a  certain  O,  it  may  happen  therefore  that  N 
shall  be  present  with  every  and  with  no  0 ;  let  the  terms  of 
.  _        ,  ,, ,   universal   absence   be    "  black."   "  snow,"   "  ani- 

|  Example  (5.)  ■  '     . 

mal ;  J  but  we  cannot  take  the  terms  or  universal 
presence,  if  M  is  present  with  a  certain  O,  and  with  a  certain 
O  not  present.  For  if  N  is  present  with  every  O,  but  M  with 
no  N,  M  will  be  present  with  no  0,  but  by  hypothesis,  it  was 
present  with  some  O,  wherefore  it  is  not  possible  thus  to  assume 
the  terms.  We  may  prove  it  nevertheless  from  the  indefinite,2 

1  Taylor  forgets  that  the  affirmation  and  negation  of  proposition  con- 
stitute its  quality,  so  construes  6/joioo-x»j/xoi/£c,  "  of  the  same  figure," — a 
classical  exactitude  procured  by  an  illogical  ambiguity.  Buhle,  "eadem 
forma." 

Ex.  5.  No  snow  is  black 

Some  animal  is  not  black 
No  animal  is  snow. 

8  Called  dStopiorog,  or  indefinite,  because  it  does  not  explain  whether 
the  attribution  is  true,  alone  in  a  part,  or  universally.    Taylor. 

Ex.  6.  Every  swan  is  white 

Some  stone  is  white 

No  stone  is  a  swan. 

Ex.  7.  Every  swan  is  white  Every  swan  is  white 

Some  bird  is  not  white  Every  bird  is  a  swan 

Every  bird  is  a  swan.  Every  bird  is  white. 


CHAP.  V.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  93 

for  since  M  was  truly  asserted  not  to  be  with  some  certain  O, 

even  if  it  is  present  with  no  0 ;  yet  being  present  with  no  O, 

there  was  not  a  syllogism,  it  is  evident,  that  neither  now  will 

there  be  one.     Again,  let  them*  be  affirmative, 

and  let  the  universal  be  similarly  assumed,  e.  g.    p0s'iu0n0sth  pro" 

let  M  be  present  with  every  N,  and  with  a  certain 

O,  N  may  happen  therefore  to  be  present,  both  with  every 

and  with  no  O,  let  the  terms  of  being  present  with  none,  be 

"white,"  "swan,"  "snow;"t  but  we  cannot  as-    .  _        ,  „, 

'  '       .  '     '         .        ...  e         t  Example  (6.) 

sume  the  terms  ot  being  present  with  every,  tor 

the  reason  which  we  have  before  stated,  but  it  may  be  shown 

from  the  indefinite.!     But  if  the   universal  be    +  _        .  ,„ , 

..,  .  +  -,  -nr  •  •  1      t  Example  (7.) 

joined  to  the  minor  extreme,  and  M  is  present  with 

no  O,  and  is  not  present  with  some  certain  N,  it  is  possible 

for  N  to  be  present  with  every  and  with  no  O ;  let  the  terms 

of  presence  be  "  white,"  "  animal,"  "  crow,"  but  of  absence, 

"  white,"  "  stone,"  "  crow."  §     But  if  the  proposi-    .  Exam  le  . 

tions  are  affirmative,  let  the  terms  of  absence  be 

"  white,"  "  animal,"  "  snow,"  of  presence,  "  white,"  "  animal," 

"swan." II     Therefore  it  is  evident,  when  the  pro-    „_        ,  ... 

e    .i,  i\J  J    *v  ||  Example  (9.) 

positions  are  ot  the  same  quality,  and  the  one 
universal,  but  the  other  particular,  that  there  is  by  no  means 
ja  syllogism.  Neither,  however,  will  there  be  one,  if  a  thing 
be  present  to  some  one  of  each  term,  or  not  present,  or  to  the 
one,  but  not  to  the  other,  or  to  neither  universally,  or  indefinitely, 
let  the  common  terms  of  all  be  "white,"  "ani-  _„        ,  ,.., 

•  •  •  iim-  "Example (10.) 

mal,    "man;     "white,    "animal,    "inanimate.  1 

Wherefore  it  is  evident,  from  what  we  have  stated,  that  if 
the  terms  subsist  towards  each  other,  as  has  been  said,  there 
is  necessarily  a  syllogism,  and  if  there  be  a  syllogism,  the 
terms  must  thus  subsist.     It  is  also  clear  that  all  syllogisms 

Ex.  8.  Some  animal  is  not  white  Some  stone  is  not  white 

No  crow  is  white  No  crow  is  white 

Every  crow  is  an  animal.  No  crow  is  a  stone. 

Ex.  9.  Some  animal  is  white  Some  animal  is  white 

All  snow  is  white  Every  swan  is  white 

No  snow  is  an  animal.  Every  swan  is  an  animal. 

Ex.  10.  Some  animal  j  j*      .  \  white     Some  animal  I  ^  not  1  white 

Some  man  |  j*      ,  j  white       Something  inanim.  I  ^  uot  I  whiU 
Every  man  is  an  animal.  Nothing  inanimate  is  an  animal. 


94  akistotle's  organon.  [book   I. 

in  this  figure  are  imperfect,  for  all  of  them  are  produced  from 
certain  assumptions,  which  are  either  of  necessity  in  the  terms, 
or  are  admitted  as  hypotheses,  as  when  we  demonstrate  by  the 
5  No  affirma-  iniP0SSit»le.  Lastly,  it  appears  that  an  affirmative 
tive  conclusion  syllogism  is  not  produced  in  this  figure,  but  all 
m  this  figure.     are   negativej   fr^  t}ie    universal  and   also  the 

particular.1 

Chap.  VI. — Of  Syllogisms  in  the  third  Figure. 

1.  •zxnu-iT'  When  with  the  same  thing  one  is  present  with 
gurejts  cha-  every,  but  the  other  with  no  individual,  or  both 
racteristic— the  with  every,  or  with  none,  such  I  call  the  third 
subject  of  both  -  figure  ;  and  the  middle  in  it,  I  call  that  of  which 
PerfecTs7io-  we  Pre^icate  both,  but  the  predicates  the  ex- 
gism  in  this  tremes,  the  greater  extreme  being  the  one  more 
figure.  remote  from  the  middle,  and  the  less,  that  which 

is  nearer  to  the  middle.  But  the  middle  is  placed  beyond  the 
extremes,  and  is  last  in  position  ;  now  neither  will  there  be  a 

perfect  syllogism,  even  in  this  figure,  but  there 
gism!'asyll°     may  De  one,*  when  the  terms  are  joined  to  the 

middle,  both  universally,  and  not  universally. 
Now  when  the  terms  are  universally  so,  when,  for  instance, 
P  and  R  are  present  with  every  S,  there  will  be  a  syllogism, 
so  that  P  will  necessarily  be  present  with  some  certain  R,  for 
since  an  affirmative  is  convertible,  S  will  be  present  to  a  cer- 
tain R.  Wherefore  since  P  is  present  to  every  S,  but  S  to 
some  certain  R,  P  must  necessarily  be  present  with  some  R, 
for  a  syllogism  arises  in  the  first  figure.     We  may  also  make 

the  demonstration  through  the  impossible,  and  by 
&T  h?*°r      exposition.2     For  if  both  are  present  with  every 

S,  if  some  S  is  assumed,  (e.  g.)  N,  both  P  and  R 

1  For  the  special  rules  and  necessary  negative  conclusion  in  this  figure, 
vide  Whately  and  Aldrich ;  and  for  the  principles  of  the  several  figures, 
compare  Hill's  Logic.  The  enumeration  of  distinct  axioms  for  the  second 
and  third  figures,  occurs  in  Lambert  Nues  Organon,  part  i.  ch.  4,  sect. 
232.  According  to  him,  the  use  of  the  second  figure  is  for  the  discovery 
and  proof  of  differences  in  things ;  and  of  the  third,  for  those  of  examples 
and  exceptions. 

2  The  method  called  tKQtaiq  signifies  by  exhibiting  an  individual  case. 
;  exponere  sensui,"  hence  a  syllogism  with  singular  premises  is  caned 

"  syllogismus  expositorius."     It   is  doubtful  whether  Aristotle  regarded 


CHAP.  VI.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  95 

will  be  present  with  this,  wherefore  P  will  he  present  with  a 
certain  R,  and  if  R  is  present  with  every  S,  but  P  is  present 
with  no  S,  there  will  be  a  syllogism,  so  that  P  will  be  neces- 
sarily inferred  as  not  present  with  a  certain  R ;  for  the  same 
mode  of  demonstration  will  take  place,  the  proposition  R  S 
being  converted ;  this  may  also  be  demonstrated  by  the  im- 
possible, as  in  the  former  syllogisms.  But  if  R  is  present 
with  no  S,  but  P  with  every  S,  there  will  not  be  a  syllogism ; 
let  the  terms  of  presence  be  "animal,"  "horse,"  "man,"  but 
of    absence    "animal,"    "inanimate,"    "man."*      „        ,  „, 

•xt   •  i  i  ii  t  ip  o         -n     *  Example  (1.) 

JN either  when  both  are  predicated  ot  no  b,  will 
there  be  a  syllogism,  let  the  terms  of  presence  be  "  animal," 
"  horse,"    "  inanimate,"  but  of  absence  "  man,"    .  _        ,  .„, 
"  horse,"  inanimate,"  the  middle  "  inanimate."  f 
Wherefore  also  in  this  figure  it  is  evident,  when  there  will, 
and   when    there   will   not,   be   a  syllogism,  the 

,     .  .  ,     n  ,  .   ■'.,    f         '  2.  When  both 

terms  being  universal,  tor  when  both  terms  are  premises  are 
affirmative,  there  will  be  a  syllogism,  in  which  it  fffirmat.i,,;ev. 

'  •>        °     .    '      ,  there  will  be  a 

will   be   concluded  that  extreme  is  with  a  cer-   syllogism,  but 
tain  extreme,1  but  when  both  terms  are  negative   "re  negative- 
there  will  not  be.    When  however  one  is  negative   the  major 
and  the  other  affirmative,  and  the  major  is  nega-   be°negatfv™ana 
tive  but  the  other  affirmative,  there  will  be  a  syl-   *he  minor> at- 

...  .  .  firmative. 

logism,   that  the   extreme    is   not  present   with 

a  certain  extreme,  but  if  the  contrary  there  will  not  be. 

If  indeed  one  be  universal  in  respect  to  the  middle,2  and  the 
other  particular,  both  being  affirmative,  syllogism  is  necessarily 
produced,  whichever  term  be  universal.     For  if  R  is  present 

the  tKOeaig  as  a  syllogism  at  all.  Vide  Aquinas,  Opusc.  47.  ZabareUa, 
cap.  7. 

Ex.  1.  Every  man  is  an  animal  Every  man  is  an  animal 

No  man  is  a  horse  No  man  is  inanimate 

Every  horse  is  an  animal.  Nothing  inanimate  is  a  horse. 

Ex.  2.  Nothing  inanimate  is  an  ani-  Nothing  inanimate  is  a  man 
mal 

Nothing  inanimate  is  a  horse  Nothing  inanimate  is  a  horsb 

Every  horse  is  an  animal.  No  horse  is  a  man. 

1  i.  e.  the  major  with  the  minor. 

*  i.  e.  Universally  predicated  of  the  middle. 

Ex.  3.   Every  animal  is  animate 
Some  animal  is  not  a  man 
Every  man  is  animate. 


9t>  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

with  every  S,  but  P  with  a  certain  S,  P  must  necessarily  be 
present  with  a  certain  R,  for  since  the  affirmative  is  convert- 
ible, S  will  be  present  with  a  certain  P,  so  that  since  R  is 
present  to  every  S,  and  S  with  a  certain  P,  R  will  also  be 
present  with  a  certain  P,  wherefore  also  P  will  be  present  with 
a  certain  R.  Again,  if  R  is  present  with  a  certain  S,  but  P  is 
present  with  every  S,  P  must  necessarily  be  present  with  a 
certain  R,  for  the  mode  of  demonstration  is  the  same,  and 
these  things  may  be  demonstrated  like  the  former,  both  by 
the  impossible,  and  by  exposition.  If  however  one  be  affirm- 
ative, and  the  other  negative,  and  the  affirmative  be  universal, 
when  the  minor  is  affirmative  there  will  be  a  syllogism  ;  for 
if  R  is  present  with  every  S,  and  P  not  present  with  a  certain 
S,  P  must  also  necessarily  not  be  present  with  a  certain  R, 
since  if  P  is  present  with  every  R,  and  R  with  every  S,  P 
will  also  be  present  with  every  S,  but  it  is  not  present,  and 
this  may  also  be  shown  without  deduction,  if  some  S  be  taken 
with  which  P  is  not  present.  But  when  the  major  is  affirm- 
ative there  will  not  be  a  syllogism,  e.  g.  if  P  is  present  with 
every  S,  but  R  is  not  present  with  a  certain  S ;  let  the  terms 
m  F  of  being  universally  present  with  be  "  animate," 

xamp  e  (i  marij"  "  animal."  *  But  it  is  not  possible  to 
take  the  terms  of  universal  negative,  if  R  is  present  with  a 
certain  S,  and  with  a  certain  S  is  not  present,  since  if  P  is 
present  with  every  S,  and  R  with  a  certain  S,  P  will  also  be 
present  with  a  certain  R,  but  it  was  supposed  to  be  present 
with  no  R,  therefore  we  must  assume  the  same  as  in  the  former 
syllogisms.  As  to  declare  something  not  present  with  a  cer- 
tain thing  is  indefinite,  so  that  also  which  is  not  present  with 
any  individual,  it  is  true  to  say,  is  not  present  with  a  certain 
individual,  but  not  being  present  with  any,  there  was  no  syl- 
logism, (therefore  it  is  evident  there  will  be  no  syllogism).1 

1  i.  e.  when  it  is  assumed  not  to  be  present  with  a  certain  individual. 

Ex.  4.  Something  wild  is  an  animal      Something  wild  is  an  animal 
Nothing  wild  is  a  man  Nothing  wild  is  science 

Every  man  is  an  animal.  No  science  is  an  animal. 

Ex.  5.  Something  wild  is  n:t  an  ani-  Something  wild  is  not  an  animal, 
mal 

Nothing  wild  is  science  Nothing  wild  is  a  man 

No  science  is  an  animal.  Every  man  is  an  animaL 


CHAP.  VI.  _,  THE    PRIOK   ANALYTICS.  97 

But  if  the  negative  term  be  universal,  (yet  the  particular  af- 
firmative,) when  the  major  is  negative,  but  the  minor  affirm- 
ative, there  will  be  a  syllogism,  for  if  P  is  present  with  no  S, 
but  R  is  present  with  a  certain  S,  P  will  not  be  present  with 
a  certain  R,  and  again  there  will  be  the  first  figure,  the  pro- 
position R  S  being  converted.  But  when  the  minor  is  nega- 
tive, there  will  not  be  a  syllogism  ;  let  the  terms  of  presence 
be  "  animal,"  "  man,"  "  wild,"  but  of  absence,  "  animal," 
"science,"  "wild,"  the  middle  of  both,  "wild."*  #  £xam 
Nor  will  there  be  a  syllogism  when  both  are  ne- 
gative, the  one  universal,  the  other  particular :  let  the  terms 
of  absence  when  the  minor  is  universal  as  to  the  middle,  be 
"  animal,"  "  science,"  "  wild,"  (of  presence,  "  ani- 
mal," "man,"  "wild)."|  When  however  the  p  {) 
major  is  universal,  but  the  minor  particular,  let  the  terms  of 
absence  be  "crow,"  "snow,"  "white  ;"t  but  of  ,  _        ,  ,„. 

'       ,        ,  -p  -r!  •  t  Example  (6.) 

presence  we  cannot  take  the  terms,  11  R  is  present 
with  some  S,  and  with  some  is  not  present,  since  if  P  is  present 
with  every  R,  but  R  with  some  S,  P  will  also  be  present  with 
some  S,  but  it  was  supposed  to  be  present  with  no  S,  indeed 
it  may  be  proved  from  the  indefinite.  Neither  if  each  ex- 
treme be  present  or  not  present  with  a  certain  middle,  will  there 
be  a  syllogism  ;  or  if  one  be  present  and  the  other  not ;  or  if  one  be 
with  some  individual  and  the  other  with  not  every  or  indefinitely. 
But  let  the  common  terms  of  all  be,  "animal,"  "man,"  "white," 
"animal,"   "inanimate,"  "white."  S      Wherefore    ,  ^        ,  ,„, 

,.,.,.  i  ,  i  -n     §  Example  (7.) 

it  is  clear  in  this  figure  also,  when  there  will 
and  when  there  will  not  be  a  syllogism,  and  that  when  the 
terms  are  disposed  as  we  have  stated,  a  syllogism  of  necessity 
subsists,  and  that  there  should  be  a  syllogism,  it  is  necessary 
that  the  terms  should  be  thus.  It  is  also  clear  3.  No  universal 
that  all  syllogisms  in  this  figure  are  imperfect,  for  conclusion  de- 
Ex.  6-  Nothing  white  is  a  crow 

Not  every  thing  white  is  snow 
No  snow  is  a  erjw. 


Ex 


7.  Something  white  j  |S^ol  j  an  Something  white  j  .           >  an  ani- 

animal  mal 

Something  white  j  l*           a  .Something  white  1 J           >  inani- 

man  mate. 

Every  man  is  an  animal.  Nothing  inanimate  is  an  animal. 


V- 


98  Aristotle's  organon.  ["book  i. 

rived  from  tMa   they  are  all  perfected  by  certain  assumptions,  and 
figure.  t[iat  an  universal  conclusion  either  negative  or  af- 

firmative, cannot  be  drawn  from  this  figure.1 

Chap.  VII. — Of  the  three  first  Figures,  and  of  the  Completion 
of  Incomplete  Syllogisms. 

In  all  the  figures  it  appears  that  when  a  syllogism  is  not  pro- 
duced, both  terms  being  affirmative,  or  negative,  (and  par- 
ticular,2) nothing,  in  short,  results  of  a  necessary  character ; 
but  if  the  one  be  affirmative  and  the  other  nega- 

1.   If  one  pre-        .  ,  ...  .  ..       .    ,  ., 

mise  be  a  or  i,  tive,  the  negative  being  universally  taken,  there 

therehwmhoeEa  *s  always  a  syllogism  of  the  minor  extreme  with  the 

conclusion  in  major.     For  example,  if  A  is  present  with  every 

norfe  predi™1  or  with  some  B,  but  B  is  present  with  no  C,  the 

oated  of  the  propositions  being  converted,  C  must  necessarily 

major.  ,  .  »  i        •       1  1 

not  be  present  with  some  A ;  so  also  in  the  other 
figures,  for  a  syllogism  is  always  produced  by  conversion  : 
again,  it  is  clear  that  an  indefinite  taken  for  a  particular  affirm- 
ative, will  produce  the  same  syllogism  in  all  the  figures. 

Moreover  it  is  evident  that  all  incomplete  syllogisms 
are  completed  by  means  of  the  first  figure,  for  all  of  them 
are  concluded,  either  ostensively  or  per  impossibile,  but 
in  both  ways  the  first  figure  is  produced  :  being  osten- 
sively*3 completed,  (the  first  figure  is  produced,) 
because  all  of  them  were  concluded  by  conversion, 
but  conversion  produces  the  first  figure  :  but  if  they  are  de- 

1  Vide  Hill,  p.  196;  also  Whately,  pp.  60  and  61.  For  the  uses  of 
the  three  figures  also  Aldrich,  iii.  8. 

2  The  words  "  and  particular  "  are  omitted  by  Waitz. 

3  Taylor  translates  this  "  demonstratively."  "  Simplici  et  rect&  de- 
monstratione."  Buhle.  Reduction  is  expressed  by  the  verb  avaytaQai, 
never  aTraytoQai.  Mansel.  He  is  also  right  in  drawing  attention  to  the 
incorrectness  of  the  phrase,  " reductio  ad  impossibile;"  it  ought  to  be 
"  per  deductionem  ad  impossibile,  or  elliptically,  per  impossibile."  The 
general  phrase  is  a  palpable  absurdity.  Vide  An.  ii.  11,  C.  Upon  the 
nature  of  the  dirayu/yr]  els  to  dSvvarov,  wherein,  after  all,  the  word  does 
not  mean  reduction,  see  Mansel's  Logic,  Appendix,  note  G.  The  anti- 
thesis to  duicTiicbg,  is  t£  V7ro9ecno)g.  Cf.  ch.  23  of  this  1st  book  of  Ana- 
lytics:  also  Whately,  book  ii.  ch.  3,  sect.  5  and  6.  Although  the  in- 
direct moods  have  been  attributed  to  the  invention  of  Theophrastus,  by 
Alexander,  (Schol.  p.  153,)  we  find  two  of  them  recognised  here  by 
Aristotle,  and  the  other  three  in  Anal.  Prior,  ii.  1. 


CHAP.  VII.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  99 

monstrated  per  impossibile,  (there  will  be  still  the  first  figure,) 
because  the  false  being  assumed,  a  syllogism  arises  in  the  first 
figure.  For  example,  in  the  last  figure,  if  A  and  B  are  present 
with  every  C,  it  can  be  shown  that  A  is  presentwith  some  B,  for 
if  A  is  present  with  no  B,  but  B  is  present  with  every  C,  A  will 
be  present  with  no  C  ;  but  it  was  supposed  that  A  was  present 
with  every  C,  and  in  like  manner  it  will  happen  in  other  in- 
stances. 

It   is   also  possible    to    reduce    all   syllogisms   ,  A11    llo 
to  universal  syllogisms  in  the  first  figure.     For   gisms  may  be 
those  in  the  second,  it  is  evident,  are  completed   vers^inth* 
through  these,  yet  not  all  in  like  manner,  but   first  figure 
the  universal  by  conversion  of  the  negative,  and   the  various 
each  of  the  particular,  by  deduction  per  impos-   methods- 
sibile.     Now,  particular  syllogisms  in  the  first  figure  are  com- 
pleted through  themselves,  but  may  in  the  second  figure  be 
demonstrated  by  deduction  to  the  impossible.     For  example, 
if  A  is  present  with  every  B,  but  B  with  a  certain  C,  it  can 
be  shown  that  A  will  be  present  with  a  certain  C,  for  if  A  is 
present  with  no  C,  but  is  present  with  every  B,  B  will  be 
present  with  no  C,  for  we  know  this  by  the  second  figure.     So 
also  will  the  demonstration  be  in  the  case  of  a  negative,  for  if 
A  is  present  with  no  B,  but  B  is  present  with  a  certain  C, 
A  will  not  be  present  with  a  certain  C,  since  if  A  is  present 
with  every  C,  and  with  no  B,  B  will  be  present  with  no  C, 
and  this  was  the  middle  figure.     Wherefore,  as  all  syllogisms 
in  the  middle  figure  are  reduced  to  universal  syllogisms  in  the 
first  figure,  but  particular  in  the  first  are  reduced  to  those  in 
the  middle  figure,  it  is  clear  that  particular  will  be  reduced  to 
universal  syllogisms  in  the  first  figure.     Those,  however,  in  the 
third,  when  the  terms  are  universal,  are  immediately  completed 
through  those  syllogisms  ;  * '    but  when  particular   ,  . 
(terms)  are  assumed  (they  are  completed)  through   versais  of  the 
particular  syllogisms  in  the  first  figure  ;  but  these  j    j! ^e^particu- 
have  been  reduced  to  those,J  so  that  also  particu-   ia«. 
lar  syllogisms  in  the  third  figure  (are  reducible         niversa  s- 
to  the  same).     Wherefore,  it  is  evident  that  all  can  be  re- 
duced to  universal  syllog'»;ms  in  the  first  figure  ;  and  we  have 
therefore  shown  how  syllogisms  de  inesse  and  de  non  inesse 

1  By  a  deduction  to  an  absurdity. 
h  2 


100  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

subsist,  both  those  which  are  of  the  same  figure,  with  refer- 
ence to  themselves,  and  those  which  are  of  different  figures, 
also  with  reference  to  each  other. 


Chap.  VIII. — Of  Syllogisms  derived  from  two  necessary 
Propositions. 

Since  however  to  exist,  to  exist  necessarily,  and 
syllogisms,  viz.  to  exist  contingently  are  different,  (for  many 
xe°if— and  those  tnmgs  exist,  but  not  from  necessity,  and  others 
to?  'avaticatov  neither  necessarily,  nor  in  short  exist,  yet  may  hap- 
tl7/xe<rt>a™cL  pen  to  exist,)  it  is  evident  that  there  will  be  a 
whateiy,  b.  2.     different  syllogism  from  each  of  these,  and  from  the 

terms  not  being  alike  ;  but  one  syllogism  will  con- 
sist of  those  which  are  necessary,  another  of  absolute,  and  a  third 
„  „  of  contingent.     In   necessary  syllogisms   it  will 

2.  Necessary  °  J  .     J ..     ° 

syllogisms  re-  almost  always  be  the  same,  as  m  the  case  of  abso- 
any  those  "er~  mte  subsistences,1  for  the  terms  being  similarly 
which  are  abso-  placed  in  both  absolute  existence,  and  in  existing, 
or  not  of  necessity,  there  will  and  there  will  not 
be  a  syllogism,  except  that  there  will  be  a  difference  in  neces- 
sary or  non-necessary  subsistence  being  added  to  the  terms. 
For  a  negative  is  in  like  manner  convertible,  and  we  assign 
similarly  to  be  in  the  whole  of  a  thing,  and  to  be  (predicated) 
of  every.  In  the  rest  then  it  will  be  shown  by  the  same 
manner,  through  conversion,  that  the  conclusion  is  necessary, 
as  in  the  case  of  being  present ;  but  in  the  middle  figure,  when 
the  universal  is  affirmative,  and  the  particular  negative,  and 
again,  in  the  third  figure,  when  the  universal  is  affirmative, 
but  the  particular  negative,  the  demonstration  will  not  be  in 
the  like  manner  ;  but  it  is  necessary  that  proposing  something 
with  which  either  extreme  is  not  present,  we  make  a  syllogism 
of  this,  for  in  respect  of  these  there  will  be  a  necessary  (conclu- 
sion). If,  on  the  other  hand,  in  respect  to  the  proposed  term, 
there  is  a  necessary  conclusion,  there  will  be  also  one  (a  neces- 
sary conclusion)  of  some  individual  of  that  term,  for  what  is 
proposed  is  part  of  it,  and  each  syllogism  is  formed  under  its 
own  appropriate  figure. 

1  i.  e.  Pure  categoricals. 


CHAP.  IX.]  THE   PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  101 


Chap.  IX.—  Of  Syllogisms,  whereof  one  Proposition  is  necessary,  and 
the  other  pure  in  the  first  Figure. 

It  sometimes  happens  also  that  when  one  pro-  ,   ConclUii- 

position  is  necessary,  a  necessary  syllogism  arises,1  of  a  syllogism 

not  however  from  either  proposition  indifferently,  Jtae  necePs-e" 

but  from  the  one  that  contains  the  greater  ex-  sar>' often  fo1.- 

treme.2      For  example,   if  A  is   assumed  to  be  premLt-ex-' 

necessarily  present  or  not  present  with  B,  but  B  3£,pfc*nd. 

to  be  alone  present  with  C,  for  the  premises  beino-  versais  and 

thus  assumed,  A  will  necessarily  be  present  or  partKUlars- 
not  with  C  ;  for  since  A  is  or  is  not  necessarily  present  with 
every  B,  but  C  is  something  belonging  to  B,  C 

will  evidently  of  necessity  be  one  of  these.*     If.  *.V,e-  wln  °f 

A      r>    /   i  ■       \    ■  W1"  not  "e  A. 

again,  A  ±$  (the  major)  is  not  necessary,  but  B 
C  (the  minor)  is  necessary,  there  will  not  be  a  necessary  con- 
clusion, for  if  there  be,  it  will  happen  that  A  is  necessarily 
present  with  a  certain  B,  both   by  the  first  and  the  third 
figure,  but  this  is  false,  for  B  may  happen  to  be  a  thing  of 
that  kind,  that  A  may  not  be  present  with  any  thing  of  it. 
Besides,  it  is  evident  from  the  terms,  that  there  will  not  be  a 
necessary  conclusion,  as  if  A  were  "motion,"  B   "animal," 
and  C   "man,"  for  "man"  is  necessarily  "an  animal,"  but 
neither  are  "animal"  nor  "man"  necessarily  "moved;"  so 
also  if  A  B  is  negative,  for  there  is  the  same  de- 
monstration.    In  particular  syllogisms,  however,    ^ecefeotl 
if  the  universal  is  necessary,  the  conclusion  will 
also  be  necessary,  but  if  the  particular  be,  there  will  not  be  a 
necessary  conclusion,  neither  if  the  universal  premise  be  nega- 
tive nor  affirmative.     Let  then,  in  the  first  place,  the  universal 
be  necessary,  and  let  A  be  necessarily  present  with  every  B, 

1  Theophrastus  and  Eudemus  allowed  a  necessary  conclusion  to  follow 
from  two  necessary  premises  only.    Vide  Alex.  Aphr. 

2  Majori  necessaria,  necessario  aliquid  inesse  concluditur.     Buhle. 

Ex.  1.  Every  animal  is  moved  No  animal  is  moved 

It  is  necessary  that  something  It  is  necessary  that  something  white 

white  should  be  an  animal  should  not  be  an  animal 

Therefore  something  white  is  Therefore  something  white  is  not 

moved.  moved. 

This  is  not  necessary,   for  it  [This  is  not  necessary,  because  it 

might  possibly  not  be  moved.]  may  be  moved.] 


102  apjstotle's  organon.  [book  I. 

but  B  only  be  present  with  a  certain  C  ;  it  is  necessary  therefore 
that  A  should  of  necessity  be  present  with  a  certain 
toV  1S  ^°ined  C,  for  C  is  under*  B,  and  A  was  of  necessity  pre- 
sent with  every  B.  The  same  will  occur  if  the 
syllogism  be  negative,  for  the  demonstration  will  be  the  same, 
but  if  the  particular  be  necessary,  the  conclusion  will  not  be 
+  i.  e.  though  a  necessary,  for  nothing  impossible  results,!  as  nei- 
ron-necessary    tner  {n  universal  syllogisms.     A  similar  conse- 

conclusion  og 

admitted.  quence   will  result  also  in    negatives  ;    (let  the 

t  Example (i.)    termg  be)  «  motionj»  "animal,"  " white." J 

Chap.   X. — Of  the  same  in  the  second  Figure. 

l.inthesecond  -^N  tne  second  figure,  if  the  negative  premise  be 

figure,  when  a  necessary,  the  conclusion  will  also  be  necessary, 

fo1nedSw!thSa  but  if  the  affirmative  (be  necessary,  the  conclu- 

pure  premise,  s\on)  wiH  not  be  necessary.     For  first,   let  the 

the  conclusion  '  .  -i    i         .  ,  .1 

follows  the  ne-  negative  be  necessary,  and  let  it  not  be  possible 

s^ypremls^-  for  A  to  be  in  any  B>  but  let  ik  be  present  with 
Example  and  C  alone  ;  as  then  a  negative  proposition  may  be 
converted,  B  cannot  be  present  with  any  A,  but 
A  is  with  every  C,  hence  B  cannot  be  present  with  any  C, 
§  i.  e.  belongs  for  C  is  under  §  A.  In  like  manner  also,  if  the 
*°rA-        ,       negative  be  added  tt>  C,||  for  if  A  cannot  be  with 

||  The  conclu-  °  'II 

sion  will  be  any  O,  neither  can  O  be  present  with  any  A,  but 
necessary.  j^  -g  w^h  everv  j},  so  neither  can  C  be  present 
with  any  B,  as  the  first  figure  will  again  be  produced ; 
wherefore,  neither  can  B  be  present  with  C,  since  it  is  simi- 
2.  if  the  affirm-  larly  converted.  If,  however,  the  affirmative  pre- 
ative  be  neces-  miSe  be  necessary,   the   conclusion  will  not  be 

sarv,  the  con-  p        i         a  -it  •  i 

elusion  will  necessary  ;  tor  let  A  necessarily  be  present  with 
not  be.  every  B,  and  alone  not  be  present  with  any  C, 

then  the  negative  being  converted,  we  have  the  first  figure ; 
but  it  was  shown  in  the  first,  that  when  the  major  negative 
(proposition)  is  not  necessary,  neither  will  the  conclusion  be 
necessary,  so  that  neither  in  these  will  there  be  a  necessary 
_ .      .       „      conclusion. If     Once   more,   if   the   conclusion    is 

IT  1.  e.  in  syllo-  . "  •       ' ' 

gismsofthe       necessary,  it  results  that  b  is  not  necessarily  pre- 
with"a  neSces!     sent  w^tn  a  certain  A,  for  if  B  is  necessarily  pre- 
sary  affirma-       sent  with  no  C,  neither  will  C  be  necessarily  pre- 
sent with  any  B,  but  B  is  present  necessarily  with 


CHAP.  XI.  J  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  103 

a  certain  A,  if  A  is  necessarily  present  with  every  B.  Hence, 
it  is  necessary  that  C  should  not  be  present  with  a  certain  A ; 
there  is,  however,  nothing  to  prevent  such  an  A  being  as- 
sumed, with  which  universally  C  may  be  present.  More- 
over, it  can  be  shown  by  exposition  of  the  terms,  that  the 
conclusion  is  not  simply  necessary,  but  necessary  from  the 
assumption  of  these,  e.  g.  let  A  be  "  animal,"  B  "  man,"  C 
"  white,"  and  let  the  propositions  be  similarly  assumed  :  for  it  is 
possible  for  an  animal  to  be  with  nothing  "  white,"  then  nei- 
ther will  "  man "  be  present  with  any  thing  white,  yet  not 
from  necessity,  for  it  may  happen  for  "man"  to  be  "white," 
yet  not  so  long  as  "  animal "  is  present  with  nothing  "  white," 
so  that  from  these  assumptions  there  will  be  a  necessary  con- 
clusion, but  not  simply  necessary. 

The  same  will  happen  in  particular  syllogisms,  for   ^mewith6 par- 
when  the  negative  proposition  is  universal  and  ne-   ticuiars. 
cessary,  the  conclusion  also  will  1  >e  necessary,but  when  the  affirm- 
ative is  universal  and  necessary,  and  the  negative   *  Taylor  in- 
particular,*  the  conclusion  will  not  be  necessary.    ^g'g' ™*not 
First,  then,  let  there  be  an  universal  and  necessary   which  words 
negative,  and  let  A  not  possibly  be  present  with   Bekkertandby 
any  B,  but  with  a  certain  C.     Since,  therefore,  a   Waits. 
negative  proposition  is  convertible,  B  can  neither  be  possibly 
present  with  any  A,  but  A  is  with  a  certain  C,  so  that  of 
necessity  B  is  not  present  with  a  certain  C.     Again,  let  there 
be  an  universal  and  necessary  affirmative,  and  let  the  affirm- 
ative be  attached  to  B,  if  then  A  is  necessarily  present  with 
every  B,  but  is  not  with  a  certain  C,  B  is  not  with  a  certain 
C  it  is  clear,  yet  not  from  necessity,  since  there  will  be  the 
same  terms  for  the  demonstration,  as  were  taken  in  the  case 
of  universal  syllogisms.     Neither,  moreover,  will  the  conclu- 
sion be  necessary,  if  a  particular  necessary  negative  be  taken 
as  the  demonstration  is  through  the  same  terms. 


o 


Chap.  XI. — Of  the  same  in  the  third  Figure. 

In  the  last  figure,  when  the  terms  are  universally  i.  in  this  figure 
joined  to  the  middle,1  and  both  premises  are  mfgehbenece«- 
affirmative,  if  either  of  them  be  necessary,  the   sary,  and  both 

1  That  is,  are  predicated  of  it. 


104  aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

be  a,  the  con-     conclusion  will  also  be  necessary;  and  if  one  be 

elusion  will  be  .  J  ' . 

necessary.  negative,  but  the  other  affirmative,  when  the 
negative  is  necessary,  the  conclusion  will  be  also  necessary, 
but  when  the  affirmative  (is  so,  the  conclusion)  will  not  be 

necessary.     For  first,  let  both  propositions  be1 

affirmative,  and  let  A  and  B  be  present  with 
every  C,  and  let  A  C  be  a  necessary  (proposition).  Since 
then  B  is  present  with  every  C,  C  will  also  be  present  with 
a  certain  B,  because  an  universal  is  converted  into  a  parti- 
cular :  so  that  if  A  is  necessarily  present  with  every  C,  and 
C  with  a  certain  B,  A  must  also  be  necessarily  present  with 
•  i.  e.  belongs  a  certain  B,  for  B  is  under  C,*  hence  the  first  figure 
t0  «*•  again  arises.     In  like  manner,  it  can  be  also  de- 

2nd  case.  monstrated  if  B  C  is  a  necessary  (proposition),  for 

C  is  converted  with  a  certain  A,  so  that  if  B  is  necessarily 
present  with  every  C,  (but  C  with  a  certain  A,)  B  will  also 
of  necessity  be  present  with  a  certain  A.  Again  let  A  C  be 
a  negative  (proposition),  but  B  C  affirmative,  and  let  the 
negative  be  necessary ;  as  therefore  an  affirmative  pro- 
position is  convertible,  C  will  be  present  with  some  certain 
B,  but  A  of  necessity  with  no  C,  neither  will  A  necessarily 

be  present  with  some  B,  for  B  is  under  C.  But 
ceptira6  an  eX~  ^  tne  affirmative  is  necessary,  there  will  not  be  a 

necessary  conclusion  ;  for  let  B  C  be  affirmative 
and  necessary,  but  A  C  negative  and  not  necessary ;  since 
then  the  affirmative  is  converted  C  will  also  be  with  a  cer- 
tain B  of  necessity  ;  wherefore  if  A  is  with  no  C,  but  C  with 
a  certain  B,  A  will  also  not  be  present  with  a  certain  B,  but 
t  Vide  ch  9      not  ^Yom  necessity,  f°r  it  bas  been  shown  by  the 

first  figure,f  that  when  the  negative  proposition 
is  not  necessary,  neither  will  the  conclusion  be  necessary. 
Moreover  this  will  also  be  evident  from  the  terms,  for  let  A 


i 


Taylor,  by  mistake,  reads  "necessary." 
Ex.  1.  No  horse  is  good 

It  is  necessary  that  every  horse  should  be  an  animal 

Therefore  some  animal  is  not  good. 

Ex.2.  No  horse  ?Takes 
I  sleeps 

It  is  necessary  that  every  horse  should  be  an  animal 

. ' .    Some  animal  does  not  \  ^ake 

I  sleep. 


CHAP.  XI.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  105 

be  "good,"  B  "animal,"  and  C  "horse,"  it  happens  therefore 

that  "good"  is  with  no  "horse,"  but  "animal"  is  necessarily 

present  with  every  "  horse,"  but  it  is  not  however  necessary 

that  a  certain  "  animal  "  should   not  be  "  good,"  for   every 

"animal"  may  possibly  be  "good."*     Or  if  this 

is  not  possible,  (viz.  that  every  animal  is  good,)  we 

must  assume  another  term,  as  "to  wake,"  or  "to  sleep,"  for 

every  "  animal "  is  capable  of  these. f     If  then  the 

terms  are  universal  in  respect  to  the  middle,  it  has 

been  shown  when  there  will  be  a  necessary  conclusion. 

But  if  one  term  is  universally  but  the  other  2.  if  0ne  pro- 
particularly  (predicated  of  the  middle),  and  both  position  be  a 
propositions  are  affirmative,  when  the  universal  is  necessary  the 
necessary  the  conclusion  will  also  be  necessary,   conclusion  's  t 

n         i        i  ...  in  •  necessary,  but 

for  the  demonstration  is  the  same  as  before,  since   not  when  i  is 
the  particular  affirmative  is  convertible.     If  there-   neeessary- 
fore  B  is  necessarily  present  with  every  C,  but  A  is  under  C, 
B  must  also  necessarily  be  present  with  a  certain  A,1  and  if 
B  is  with  a  certain  A,  A  must  also  be  present  necessarily  with 
a  certain  B,  for  it  is  convertible ;  the  same  will  also  occur  if 
A  C  be  a  necessary  universal  proposition,  for  B  is  under  C. 
But  if  the  particular  be  necessary,  there  will  not  be  a  neces- 
sary conclusion,  for  let  B  C  be  particular  and  necessary,  and 
A  present  with  every  C,  yet  not  of  necessity,  B  C  then  being 
converted  we  have  the  first  figure,  and  the  universal  propo- 
sition is  not  necessary,  but  the  particular  is  necessary,  but 
when  the  propositions  are  thus  there  was  not  a  necessary  con- 
clusion,^: so  that  neither  will  there  be  one  in  the 
case  of  these.  §     Moreover  this  is  evident  from  the   *  Ex^ie  tf ) 
terms,  for  let  A  be  "  wakefulness,"  B  "  biped,"  but 
C,  "animal ;"  B  then  must  necessarily  be  present  with  a  cer- 

1  This  succeeding  clause  is  omitted  by  Taylor,  though  read  by  Buhle 

and  Waitz. 

Ex.  3.  Every  C  is  A. 

t.  ■  ,,  (  C  should  be  B 

It  is  necessary  that  some  <  „    ,      , ,  £    ~ 

.  •  .    Some  B  is  A. 

Ex.  4.  Every  animal  wakes 

It  is  necessary  that  some  anim:il  should  be  biped 
.  • .    Some  biped  wakes. 


106  Aristotle's  org  axon.  [book  i. 

tain  C,  but  A  may  happen  to  be  present  with  every  C,  and 
yet  A  is  not  necessarily  so  with  B,  for  a  certain  "  biped  "  need 

not  "  sleep  "  or  "  wake."  *  So  also  we  may  de- 
t  Example  (5 )    monstrate  it  by  the  same  terms  if  A  be  particular 

and  necessary.f  But  if  one  term  be  affirmative 
and  the  other  negative,  when  the  universal  proposition  is  ne- 
gative and  necessary,  the  conclusion  will  also  be  necessary, 
for  if  A  happens  to  no  C,  but  B  is  present  with  a  certain  C, 
A  must  necessarily  not  be  present  with  a  certain  B.  But 
3  when  the  when  the  affirmative  is  assumed  as  necessary, 
affirmative  is  whether  it  be  universal  or  particular,  or  particular 
am  i?or when  negative,  there  will  not  be  a  necessary  conclusion, 
o  is  assumed,     for   we    mav    allege    the    other    same    (reasons 

there  will   not  \ 

be  a  necessary  against  it),  as  m  the  former  cases.1  But  let  the 
conclusion.  terms  when  the  universal  affirmative  is  necessary 
♦  it        ,  ,,,   be   "wakefulness,"  "animal,"  "man,"  the  middle 

t  Example  (6.)  '  '     ,  ' 

"man.  J  But  when  the  particular  affirmative  is 
necessary,  let  the  terms  be  "wakefulness,"  "animal,"  "  white," 
for  "animal"  must  necessarily  be  with  something  "white,"  but 
"wakefulness"  happens  to  be  with  nothing  "white,"  and  it 

is  not  necessary  that  wakefulness  should  not  be 
§  Example  (7.)   wjth  a  certain  animal. §     But  when  the  negative 

particular  is  necessary,  let  the  terms  be  "biped," 
xampe(.)   it mo^on»    "animal,"    and    the     middle     term, 

"  animal."  || 

Ex.  5.  It  is  necessary  that  some  ani-  Every  animal  wakes 

mal  should  be  a  biped  It  is  necessary  that  some  biped 

Every  animal  wakes  should  be  an  animal 

.  * .  Something  that  wakes  is  a     .  ' .  Some  biped  wakes, 
biped. 
1  Because  by  reduction  to  the  first  figure  the  minor  will  be  necessary, 
but  the  major  pure ;    hence  no  necessary  conclusion  can  be  inferred. 
(Vide  supra.) 

Ex.  6.  Some  man  does  not  wake 

It  is  necessary  that  every  man  should  be  an  animal 
.  • .    Some  animal  does  not  wake. 

Ex.  7.  Nothing  white  wakes 

It  is  necessary  that  something  white  should  be  an  animal 
.  • .  Some  animal  does  not  wake. 

Ex.  8.  It  is  necessary  that  some  animal  should  not  be  a  biped 
Every  animal  is  moved 
• .     Something  which  is  moved  is  not  a  biped. 


CHAP.  Xn.    Xm.]       THE    PRIOR    ANALTTICS.  107 


Chap.  XII. — A  comparison  of  pure  loitli  necessary  Syllogisms? 

It  appears  then,  that  there  is   not  a  syllogism  de  inesse  un- 
less both   propositions   signify  the  being  present  with,2  but 
that  a  necessary  conclusion  follows,  even  if  one 
alone  is  necessary.  But  in  both,*  the  syllogisms   anciniodai6 
being  affirmative,  or  negative,  one  of  the  propo- 
sitions must  necessarily  be  similar  to  the  conclu-    1.  Distinction 
sion  ;  I  me  in  by  similar,  that  if  (the  conclusion)    solute6  and  ne*- 
be  (simply)  that  a  thing  is  present  with,  (one  of  cessaryconciu- 
the  propositions  also  signifies  simply)  the  being  pre-   th°e" latter^? ab- 
sent with,  but  if  necessarily,  (that  is,  in  the  con-    pendence  upon 

,.  ,,    ,  .   .      v     .        ,    \  the  premises ; 

elusion,  one  of  the  propositions  is  also)  necessary,  theirconnexion 
Wherefore  this  also  is  evident,  that  there  will  als0Wlthlt- 
neither  be  a  conclusion  necessary  nor  simple  de  inesse,  unless 
one  proposition  be  assumed  as  necessary,  or  purely  categorical, 
and  concerning  the  necessary,  how  it  arises,  and  what  differ- 
ence it  has  in  regard  to  the  de  inesse,  we  have  almost  said 
enough. 


Chap.  XIII. — Of  the   Contingent,  and  its  concomitant  Propositions. 

Let  us  next  speak  of  the  contingent,  when,  and  ,  Definit;on  0f 

how,  and  through  what  (propositions)  there  will  the_  contingent 

be  a  syllogism  ;   and  to  be  contingent,  and  the  \™t  gVeXn"and 

contingent,  I  define  to  be  that  which,  not  being  confirmed. 

v     4.    l     •  A    4.  -\  4-U-  (VideMetaph. 

necessary,  but   being  assumed  to  exist,  nothing   ijD.  v.  2,)  also 
impossible  will  on  this  account  arise,  for  we  say   InterPret- 13- 
that  the  necessary  is  contingent  equivocally.     But,  that  such 

1  Vide  the  previous  notes  on  the  subject  of  modals.  The  reader  who 
wishes  to  ascertain  how  far  logic  is  conversant  with  the  expressed  matter  of 
modal  proposition,  will  find  arguments  "  ad  rem,"  and  "  ad  nauseam" 
both,  in  relation  to  the  various  views  of  the  question,  in  Ed.  Review,  No. 
118;  Kant,  Logik,  sec.  30;  St.  Hilaire's  preface.  In  both  modals  and 
pure  categoricals,  the  format  consequence  alone  is  really  the  legitimate 
object  of  consideration  to  the  logician,  with  the  material  he  has  strictly 
nothing  to  do.  Whately  has  shown  that  a  modal  may  be  stated  as  a  pure 
proposition,  by  attaching  the  mode  to  one  of  the  terms  ;  this  being  done, 
the  rule  of  consequence  applies  to  both  equally. 

2  i.  e.  in  categoricals  both  premises  must  be  affirmative  for  the  con- 
clusion to  be  so. 


108  Aristotle's  oroanon.  [rook  i. 

is  the  contingent,  is  evident  from  opposite  negatives  and 
affirmatives,  for  the  assertions — "  it  does  not  happen  to  be," 
and,  "  it  is  impossible  to  be,"  and,  "  it  is  necessary  not  to  be," 
are  either  the  same,  or  follow  each  other  ;  wherefore  also  the 
contraries  to  these,  "  it  happens  to  be,"  "  it  is  not  impossible 
to  be,"  and,  "  it  is  not  necessary  not  to  be,"  will  either  be  the 
same,  or  follow  each  other  ;  for  of  every  thing,  there  is  either 
affirmation  or  negation,  hence  the  contingent  will  be  not 
necessary,  and  the  not-necessary  will  be  contingent.  It  hap- 
pens, indeed,  that  all  contingent  propositions  are 
Trpimio-e!!-  ca-  convertible  with  each  other.  I  do  not  mean  the 
versfoif  C°n  affirmative  into  the  negative,  but  as  many  as  have 
an  affirmative  figure,  as  to  opposition  ;  e.  g.  "  it 
happens  to  exist,"  (is  convertible  into)  "  it  happens  not  to 
exist,"  and,  "  it  happens  to  every,"  into  "  it  happens  to  none," 
or,  "not  to  every,"  and,  "it  happens  to  some,"  into  "  it  hap- 
pens not  to  some."  In  the  same  manner  also  with 
sioifeffectel""  tne  rest,*  for  since  the  contingent  is  non-neces- 
sary, and  the  non-necessary  may  happen  not  to 
exist,  it  is  clear  that  if  A  happens  to  be  with  any  B,  it  may 
also  happen  not  to  be  present,  and  if  it  happens  to  be  present 
with  every  B,  it  may  also  happen  not  to  be  pi'esent  with  every 
B.  There  is  the  same  reasoning  also  in  particular  affirmatives, 
for  the  demonstration  is  the  same,  but  such  propositions  are 
affirmative  and  not  negative,  for  the  verb  "  to  be  contingent," 
.  „.„      „        is  arranged  similarly  to  the  verb  "  to  be,"  as  we 

t  Vide  c.  3.  °  * 

have  said  before. \ 
„  „,         .  These  things  then  being  defined,  let  us  next 

3.  The  contin-  o  ' 

gent  predicated  remark,  that  to  be  contingent  is  predicated  in  two 

the'rae Serai  ways>  one  tnat  which  happens  for  the  most  part 

the  other  inde-  and  yet  falls  short  of  the  necessary — (for  instance, 

th^of  conver-  f°r  a  man  t°  become  hoary,  or  to  grow,  or  to 

sion  not  the  waste,  or  in  short  whatever  may  naturally  be,  for 

Si  line  to  63.cn 

this  has  not  a  continued  necessity,  for  the  man 
may  not  always  exist,  but  while  he  does  exist  it  is  either  of 
necessity  or  for  the  most  part) x — the  other  way  (the  contin- 
gent is)  indefinite,  and  is  that  which  may  be  possibly  thus  and 
not  thus  ;  as  for  an  animal  to  walk,  or  while  it  is  walking  for  an 
earthquake  to  happen,  or  in  short  whatever  occurs  casually,  for 

i 
1  i.  e.  that  he  is  subject  to  these  things. 


CHAP.  XIII. ]  THE    Pivxo..   ANALYTICS.  109 

nothing  is  more  naturally  produced  thus,  or  in  a  contrary  way. 
Each  kind  of  contingent  however  is  convertible  according  to 
opposite  propositions,  yet  not  in  the  same  manner,  but  what 
may  naturally  subsist  is  convertible  into  that  which  does  not 
subsist  of  necessity  ;  thus  it  is  possible  for  a  man  not  to  be- 
come hoary,  but  the  indefinite  is  converted  into  what  cannot 
more  subsist  in  this  than  in  that  way.  Science  however  and 
demonstrative  syllogism  do  not  belong  to  indefinites,  because 
the  middle  is  irregular,  but  to  those  things  which  may  na- 
turally exist ;  and  arguments  and  speculations  are  generally 
conversant  with  such  contingencies,  but  of  the  indefinite  con- 
tingent we  may  make  a  syllogism,  though  it  is  not  generally 
investigated.  These  things  however  will  be  more 
defined  in  what  follows,1  at  present  let  us  show  n'ite  contingent 
when  and  how  and  what  will  be  a  syllogism  from   of  less  use  in 

^       °  syllogism. 

contingent  propositions. 

Since  then  that  this  happens  to  be  present  with  that  may 
be  assumed  in  a  twofold  respect, — (for  it  either  signifies 
that  with  which  this  is  present,  or  that  with  which  it  may  be 
present,  thus  the  assertion,  A  is  contingent  to  that  of  which 
B  is  predicated,  signifies  one  of  these  things,  either  that  of 
which  B  is  predicated,  or  that  of  which  it  may  be  predicated ; 
but  the  assertion  that  A  is  contingent  to  that  of  which  there 
is  B,  and  that  A  may  be  present  with  every  B,  do  not  differ 
from  each  other,  whence  it  is  evident  that  A  may  happen  to 
be  present  with  every  B  in  two  ways,) — let  us  first  show  if  B 
is  contingent  to  that  of  which  there  is  C,  and  if  A  is  contin- 
gent to  that  of  which  there  is  B,  what  and  what  kind  of  syllo- 
gism there  will  be,  for  thus  both  propositions  are  contingently 
assumed.     When  however  A  is  contingent  to  that     '       . 

.  .   .         .      ,      .  5.  An  inquiry 

with  which  B  is  present,  one  proposition  is  de  in-   into  the  con- 
esse,  but  the  other  of  that  which  is  contingent,  so   contingent'syt- 
that  we  must  begin  from  those  of  similar  character,   logisms  pre- 

*— ■*  Tin  fpfi 

as  we  began  elsewhere.2 

1  In  the  Post  Analytics,  i.  c.  8.  In  Rhetoric,  b.  ii.  c.  24,  he  admits  ac- 
cident to  be  an  element  of  apparent  argument,  but  in  Metap.  lib.  v.  c>  3, 
denies  that  there  is  any  science  of  it,  and  regards  it  as  a  <xt]fitlov. 

7  That  is,  from  syllogisms,  each  of  whose  propositions  is  contingent. 


110 


ARISTOTLE  S    ORGANON. 


[BOOK   I. 


Chap.  XIV.  —  Of  Syllogisms  ivitA  two  continyeut  P rojjusitions  in 

the  first  Fiyure. 


When  A  is  contingent  to  every  B,  and  B  to 
every  C,  there  will  be  a  perfect  syllogism,  so  that 
A  is  contingent  to  every  C,  which  is  evident  from 
the  definition,  for  thus  we  stated  the  universal 
contingent  (to  imply).  So  also  if  A  is  contingent 
to  no  B,  but  B  to  every  C,  (it  may  be  concluded)  that  A  is 
contingent  to  no  C,  for  to  affirm  that  A  is  contin- 
gent in  respect  of  nothing  to  which  B  is  contin- 
gent, this  were  to  leave  none  of  the  contingents  which  are 
under  B.  But  when  A  is  contingent  to  every  B,  but  B  con- 
tingent to  no  C,  no  syllogism  arises  from  the  as- 
sumed propositions,  but  B  C1  being  converted  ac- 
cording to  the  contingent,  the  same  syllogism  arises  as  existed 
before,  as  since  it  happens  that  B  is  present  with  no  C,  it  may 
also  happen  to  be  present  with  every  C,  which  was 
shown  before,*  wherefore  if  B  may  happen  to 
every  C,  and  A  to  every  B,  the  same  syllogism  will  again 
arise.  The  like  will  occur  also  if  negation  be  added  with  the 
contingent  (mode)  to  both  propositions,  I  mean,  as 
if  A  is  contingent  to  no  B,  and  B  to  no  C,  no  syl- 
logism arises  through  the  assumed  propositions,  but  when  they 
2  when  the  are  converted  there  will  be  the  same  as  before.  It 
ooXneiLuve  *s  ev^ent  tnen  tnat  when  negation  is  added  to 
or  the  minor  the  minor  extreme,  or  to  both  the  propositions, 
is6 either  no  ere  there  is  either  no  syllogism,  or  an  incomplete  one, 
syllogism  or  an   for  the  necessity  (of  consequence)  is  completed  by 

incomplete  one  .  T;   ;  1  „  '  ,  l         .   .      J 

—case  of  the  conversion.  It  however  one  ot  the  propositions 
versai  with  th  ^e  universal,  and  the  other  be  assumed  as  parti- 
minor  particu-    cular,  the  universal  belonging  to  the  major  ex- 

lar,  different.        treme  there    ^    bg  ft  perfect   syHogism>  for  if   A 

is  contingent  to  every  B,  but  B  to  a  certain  C,  A  is  also  con- 
tingent to  a  certain  C,  and  this  is  clear  from  the  definition  of 
universal  contingent.  Again,  if  A  is  contingent  to  no  B,  but 
B  happens  to  be  present  with  some  C,  it  is  necessary  that  A 
should  happen  not  to  be  present  with  some  C,  since  the  de- 


1.  With  the 
contingent  pre- 
mises both  uni- 
versal there 
will  be  a  perfect 
syllogism. 


2nd  case. 


3rd  case. 


»  Vide  ch.  13. 


4th  case. 


That  is,  the  minor  negative  being  made  ^Affirmative. 


CHAP.  XIV.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  1  1  i 

monstration  is  the  same  ;  but  if  the  particular  proposition  be 
assumed  as  negative,  and  the  universal  affirmative,  and  retain 
the  same  position  as  if  A  happens  to  be  present  to  every  B, 
but  B  happens  not  to  be  present  with  some  C,  no  evident 
syllogism  arises  from  the  assumed  propositions,  but  the  parti- 
cular being  converted  and  B  being  assumed  to  be  contingently 
present  with  some  C,  there  will  be  the  same  conclusion  as  be- 
fore in  the  first  syllogisms.1  Still  if  the  major  proposition  be 
taken  as  particular,  but  the  minor  as  universal,  and  2  Vice  versa 
if  both  be  assumed  affirmative  or  negative,  or  of 
different  figure,  or  both  indefinite  or  particular,  there  will 
never  be  a  syllogism  ;  for  there  is  nothing  to  prevent  B  from 
being  more  widely  extended  than  A,  and  from  not  being 
equally  predicated.  Now  let  that  by  which  B  exceeds  A,  be 
assumed  to  be  C,  to  this  it  will  happen 2  that  A  is  present 
neither  to  every,  nor  to  none,  nor  to  a  certain  one,  nor  not 
to  a  certain  one,  since  contingent  propositions  are  convertible, 
and  B  may  happen  to  be  present  to  more  things  than  A. 
Besides,  this  is  evident  from  the  terms,  for  when  the  propo- 
sitions are  thus,  the  first  is  contingent  to  the  last,  and  to  none, 
and  necessarily  present  with  every  individual,  and  let  the 
common  terms  of  all  be  these ;  of  being  present  necessarily 3 
"  animal,"  "  white,"  "  man,"  but  of  not  being  con-  ,  Example  (]>) 
tingent,  "animal,"  "white,"  "garment."*  There- 
fore it  is  clear  that  when  the  terms  are  thus  there  is  no  syllo- 

1  In  the  universal  imperfect  syllogisms  mentioned  towards  the  begin- 
ning of  this  chapter. 

8  Because  C  is  necessarily  not  present,  and  the  necessary  is  distin- 
guished from  the  contingent. 

3  That  is,  of  the  major  being  with  the  minor. 

Ex.  1.  It  happens  that  something  white  j  |s         >  an  animal 

!  every        \ 
c?  >  man  is  white 

not  every  / 
It  is  necessary  that  every  man  should  be  an  animal. 

It  happens  that  something  white     jt  not  I  an  animeJ 

I  every        \ 
n°   „         >  garment  is  white 
oW  1X1 C 
not  every  / 
It  is  necessary  that  no  garment  should  be  an  wiimsj. 


112  aristotle's  orgajston.  [book  i, 

gism,  for  every  syllogism  is  either  de  inesse,  or  of  that  which 
exists  necessarily  or  contingently,  but  that  this  is  neithei 
tie  inesse,  nor  of  that  which  necessarily  exists,  is  clear,  since 
the  affirmative  is  subverted  by  the  negative,  and  the  negative 
by  the  affirmative,  wherefore  it  remains  that  it  is  of  the  con- 
tingent, but  this  is  impossible,  for  it  has  been  shown  that  when 
the  terms  are  thus,  the  first  is  necessarily  inherent  in  all  the 
last,  and  contingently  is  present  with  none,  so  that  there 
cannot  be  a  syllogism  of  the  contingent,  for  the  necessary  is 
not  contingent.  Thus  it  is  evident  that  when  universal  terms 
3.  when  the  are  assumed  in  contingent  propositions,  there 
unTJersaiaAor  arises  always  a  syllogism  in  the  first  figure,  both 
e,  there  is  ai-  when  they  are  affirmative  and  negative,  except 
Jsm  in  tL  first  tnat  being  affirmative  it  is  complete,  but  if  nega- 
flgure-the         \[Yq  incomplete,  we  must  nevertheless  assume  the 

former(A)  com-  .  ,  .  .   . 

piete— the  lat-  contingent  not  in  necessary  propositions,  but  ac- 
piete^  rvide"  cor(ling  to  the  before-named  definition,  and  sorae- 
last  chapter.)     times  a  thing  of  this  kind  escapes  notice. 

Chap.  XV. — Of  Syllogisms  with  one  simple  and  another  contingent 
Proposition  in  the  first  Figure. 

.  „     „    .       If  one  proposition  be  assumed  to  exist,  but  the 

1.  No  svlloffism 

with  mixed  other  to  be  contingent,  when  that  which  contains 
aodmodai^tf  tne  maj0r  extreme  signifies  the  contingent,  all  the 
the  major  is  syllogisms  will  be  perfect  and  of  the  contingent,  ac- 
syHoKismwiu6  cording  to  the  above  definition.  But  when  the  mi- 
be  perfect,  not  nor  rls  contingent)  they  will  all  be  imperfect,  and 

otherwise. 

the  negative  syllogisms  will  not  be  of  the  contingent, 
according  to  the  definition,  but  of  that  which  is  necessarily 
present  with  no  one  or  not  with  every  ;  for  if  it  is  necessarily 
present  with  no  one,  or  not  with  every,  we  say  that  "  it  hap- 
pens "  to  be  present  with  no  one  and  not  with  every.  Now 
let  A  be  contingent  to  every  B,  and  let  B  be  assumed  to  be 
present  with  every  C,  since  then  C  is  (included)  under  B,  and 

Ai?  contingent  to  every  B,  A  is  also  clearly  con- 

1    Case  of  a.  " 

perfect  syiio-  tingent  to  every  C,  and  there  is  a  perfect  syllo- 
minorTshpuree  S*sm'  ^o  a^so  i*  tne  proposition  A  B  is  negative, 
but  B  C  affirmative,  and  A  B  is  assumed  as  con- 
tingent, but  B  C  to  be  present  with  (simply),  there  will  be  a 
perfect  syllogism,  so  that  A  will  happen  to  be  present  with  no  C. 


CHAP.  XV.]  THE    PRIOK    ANALYTICS.  113 

It  appears  then  that  when  a  pure  minor  is  assumed  the  syl- 
logisms are  perfect,  but  that  when  it  is  of  a  contrary  charac- 
ter it  may  be  shown  per  impossible  that  there  would  be  also 
syllogisms,  though  at  the  same  time  it  would  be  evident  that 
they  are  imperfect,  since  the  demonstration  will  not  arise  from 
the  assumed  propositions.  First,  however,  we  must  show  that 
if  A  exists,  B  must  necessarily  exist,  and  that  if  A  is  possible, 
B  will  necessarily  be  possible ;  let  then  under  these  circum- 
stances A  be  possible  but  B  impossible,  if  therefore  the  possible, 
since  it  is  possible  to  be,  may  be  produced,  yet  the  impossible, 
because  it  is  impossible,  cannot  be  produced.  But  if  at  the 
same  time  A  is  possible  and  B  impossible,  it  may  happen  that 
A  may  be  produced  without  B  ;  if  it  is  produced  also,  that  it 
may  exist,  for  that  which   has   been  generated,    „  „. 

i  «i  i_        i  ,  .  b,L  2-  Digression 

when  it  has  been  so  generated,  exists.  We  must  to  prove  the  na- 
however  assume  the  possible  and  impossible,1  not  consequence  in 
only  in  generation,  but  also  in  true  assertion,  and   respect  of  the 

lu  t    .  ,,  ,         possible  and 

in  the  inesse,  and  m  as  many  other  ways  as  the  impossible,  and 
possible  is  predicated,  for  the  case  will  be  the  necessary- 
same  in  all  of  them.  Moreover  (when  it  is  said)  if  A  exists 
B  is,  we  must  not  understand  as  if  A  being  a  certain  thing  B 
will  be,  for  no  necessary  consequence  follows  from  one  thing 
existing ;  but  from  there  being  two  at  least,  as  in  the  case  of 
propositions  subsisting  in  the  manner  we  have  stated  in  syllo- 
gism. For  if  C  is  predicated  of  D,  but  D  cf  F,  C  will  also 
necessarily  be  predicated  of  F ;  and  if  eacli  be  possible,  the 
conclusion  will  be  possible,  just  as  if  one  should  take  A  as  the 
premises,  but  B  the  conclusion ;  it  will  not  only  happen  that 
A  being  necessary,  B  is  also  necessary,  but  that  when  the 
former  is  possible,  the  latter  also  will  be  possible. 

This  being  proved,  it  is  manifest  that  when  3.  From  a  false 
there  is  a  false  and  not  impossible  hypothesis,  the   hypothesis,  not 

n    .1         1  f  -i,        1  ,         n  ,  impossible,  a 

consequence  of  the  hypothesis  will  also  be  false   similar  conciu- 
and  not  impossible,  e.  g.  if  A  is  false  yet  not  im-    skm  follows- 
possible,  but  when  A  is,  B  also  is, — here  B  will  also  be  false 
yet  not  impossible.     For  since  it  has  been  shown  that  A  ex- 

1  The  possible  is  either  that  which  may  be  when  it  is  not,  or  that 
which  is  simply,  or  that  which  necessarily  is  ;  and  to  all  these  the  above 
rule  applies,  and  the  formal  consequence  follows  as  directly  from  the  pre- 
mises, as  to  its  character,  as  in  the  case  of  categoricals.  Cf.  Metap.  13. 
The  nature  of  the  possible  is  fully  discussed,  Rhetoric,  b.  ii.  ch.  ID. 

i 


114  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

isting,  B  also  exists,  when  A  is  possible,  B  will  be  also  pos- 
sible, but  A  is  supposed  to  be  possible,  wherefore  B  will  be- 
also  possible,  for  if  it  were  impossible  the  same  thing  would 
be  possible  and  impossible  at  the  same  time.     These  things 
then  being  established,  let  A  be  present  with  every  B,  and 
B  contingent  to  every  C,  therefore  A  must  necessarily  hap- 
pen to  be  present  with  every   C  ;    for   let  it  not  happen, 
but  let  B  be  supposed  to  be  present  with  every  C,  this  is 
indeed   false   yet   not   impossible  ;    if  then   A   is   not   con- 
tingent to  C,  but  B  is  present  with  every  C,  A  is  not  con- 
tingent to  every  B,  for  a  syllogism  arises  in  the  third  figure. 
But  it  was  supposed  (that  A  was)  contingently  present  with 
every  (B),  therefore  A  must  necessarily  be  contingent  to  every 
C,  for  the  false  being  assumed,  and  not  the  im- 
xampe(.     p^g^^i  the  consequence  is  impossible.*      We 
may  also  make  a  deduction  to  the  impossible  in  the  first  figure 
by  assuming  B  to  be  present  with  every  C,  for  if  B  is  with 
every  C,  but  A  contingent  to  every  B,  A  will  also  be  contin- 
gent to  every  C,  but  it  was  supposed  not  to  be 
present  with  every  C.f     Still  we  must  assume 
the  being  present  with  every,  not  distinguishing  it  by  time,  as 
4  u  -    rs  l        "  nowj"  or  "  at  tms  time,"  but  simply ;  for  by  pro- 
predication  has   positions  of  this  kind,  we  also  produce  syllogisms,2 

1  i.  e.  that  A  is  not  contingent  to  every  C. 

Ex.  1.  Every  B  is  A  It  is  necessary  that  some  C 

should  not  be  A 

It  happens  that  every  C  is  B  Every  C  is  B 

.  • .    It  happens  that  every  C  is  A.  .  • .  Not  every  B  is  A. 

Ex.  2.  Every  B  is  A  It  happens  that  every  B  is  A 

It  happens  that  every  C  is  B  Every  C  is  B 

.  •  .    It  happens  that  every  C  is  A.  .  •  .  It  happens  that  every  C  is  A. 

2  Vide  note  to  chap.  13,  also  Post  Anal.  Book  i.  He  takes  only  pro- 
positions which  are  universally  and  immutably  true  for  the  elements  of 
the  sciences. 

Ex.  3.  Whatever  is  moved  is  a  man  Whatever  is  moved  is  an  animal 

It  happens  that  every  horse  It   happens   that    every    man    is 

is  moved  moved 

It  is  necessary  that  no  horse  It  is   necessary  that   every   man 

should  be  a  man.  should  be  an  animal. 

Ex.  4.  No  B  is  A  It  is  necessary  that  some  C 

should  be  A 

It  happens  that  every  C  is  B  Every  C  is  B 

.  •  .    Ii  happens  that  no  C  is  A.  .  '  .  Some  B  is  A. 


CHAP.  XV.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  115 

since  when  a  proposition  is  taken  as  to  the  pre-  no  reference  to 
sent  it  will  not  be  syllogism,  since  perhaps  there  ri^an^imr* 
is  nothing  to  hinder  "  man  "  from  being  present  Logic.) 
some  time  or  other  with  every  thing  moved,  viz.  if  nothing  else 
is  moved,  but  what  is  moved  is  contingent  to  every  "  horse," 
yet  "man"  is  contingent  to  no  "horse."  Moreover,  let  the 
first  term  be  "  animal,"  the  middle,  "  that  which  is  moved," 
and  the  last,  "man  ;"  the  propositions  will  then  be  alike,  but 
the  conclusion  necessary,  and  not  contingent,  for  "  man  "  is 
necessarily  "  an  animal,"  so  that  it  is  evident  that  the 
universal  must  be  taken  simply  and  not  deprived  g  £xam  lg  . 
by  time.* 

Again,  let  the  proposition  A  B  be  universal  negative,  and 
let  A  be  assumed  to  be  present  with  no  B,  but   ■>.  Epure.   a 
let  B  contingently  be  present  with  every  C  ;  now   contingent, 
from  these  positions  A  must  necessarily  happen  to  be  present 
with  no  C,  for  let  it  not  so  happen,  but  let  B  be  supposed  to 
be  present  with  C,  as  before  ;    then  A  must  necessarily  be 
present  with  some  B,  for  there  is  a  syllogism  in  the  third 
figure,  but  this  is  impossible,  wherefore  A  can  be  contingent 
to  no  C,  for  the  false  and  not  the  impossible  being 
assumed,  the  impossible  results.!   Now  this  syllo-    JVWeTupra!)'! 
gism  is   not  of  the  contingent  according  to  the 
definition,  but  of  what  is  necessarily  present  with  none,  for 
this  is  a  contradiction  of  the  given  hypothesis,  because  A  was 
supposed  necessarily  present  with  some  C,  but  the  syllogism 
per  impossibile  is  of  an  opposite '  contradiction.  Besides,  from 
the  terms  it  appears  clearly  that  there  is  no  contingent  con- 
clusion, for  let  "  crow"  stand  for  A,  "  that  which  is  intelligent " 
for  B,  and  "man"  for  C  ;  A  is  therefore  present  with  no  B, 
for  nothing  intelligent  is  a  "crow;"    but  B  is  contingent  to 
every  C,  since  it  happens  to  every  "man"  to  be  "intelligent," 
but  A  is  necessarily  present  with  no  C,  where-      £xam  le 
fore    the    conclusion    is   not   contingent.^       But 
neither  is  the  conclusion  always  necessary,  for  let  A  be  "what 
is  moved,"  B  "science,"  and  C  "man,"  A  will  then  be  present 
with  no  B,  but  B  is  contingent  to  every  C,  and  the  conclusion 

!  Vide  Whately's  Logic,  b.  ii.  c.  3,  sect.  7. 

Ex.  5.  Nothing  intelligent  is  a  crow 

It  happens  that  every  man  is  intelligent 
It  is  necessary  that  no  man  should  be  a  crow. 
I  -i 


116  Aristotle's  org  anon.  [book  i. 

will  not  be  necessary,  for  it  is  not  necessary  that  no  "man" 
should  be  "moved,"  but  also  it  is  not  necessary  that  a  certain 
man  should  be  moved  ;  therefore  it  is  clear  that  the  conclu- 
sion is  of  that  which  is  necessarily  present  with  no  one,  hence 
the  terms  must  be  assumed  in  a  better  manner.1  But  if  the 
3.  Minor  nega-  negative  be  joined  to  the  minor  extreme,  signify  - 
tive  contingent.  [n„  to  ^g  contingent,  from  the  assumed  propositions 
there  will  be  no  syllogism,  but  there  will  be  as  in  the  former 

1  That  is,  instead  of  science,  or  an  abstract  term,  we  must  assume  one 
which  may  concur  with  man,  e.  g.  "scientific,"  since  a  man  may  be 
"scientific,"  though  he  cannot  be  "science." 

Ex.  6.  It  happens  that  ]  e^ery  I  ani_     it  happens  that  j  ev    -    J  animal 

mal  is  white  is  white 

No  snow  is  an  animal  No  pitch  is  an  animal 

It  is  necessary  that  all  snow  It  is  necessary  that  no  pitch  should 

should  be  white.  be  white. 

Ex.  7.  It  happens  that  I         •?  [  ani-      It  happens  that   j         ^  >  animal 

mal  is  white  is  white 

Some  snow  is  not  an  animal  Some  pitch  is  not  an  animal 

It  is  necessary  that  all  snow  It  is  necessary  that  no  pitch  should 

should  be  white.  be  white. 

Ex.  8.  It  happens  that  \  sometnmg  I  white  js  an  animal 

rr  I  not  every  thing  ) 

I  Every        \ 
No  •       ,.. 

Q  „  >  man  is  white 

Some  1 

.  Not  every  / 
It  is  necessary  that  every  man  should  be  an  animal. 

It  happens  that  j  ^"etery'thing  }  white  is  an  animal 

!  Every    '     \ 
Some         (  Sarment  is  ^hite 
Not  every' 
It  is  necessary  that  no  garment  should  be  an  animal. 

xt°  .  °  .i,  •      f  white  is  an  animal 

Not  every  thing  ) 


(every 
)  man  is  white 
some         f 
not  every , 
It  is  necessary  that  every  man  should  be  an  animal. 


CHAP.  XV.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  117 

instances,  when  the  contingent  proposition  is  converted.  For 
let  A  be  present  with  every  B,  but  B  contingent  to  no  C, 
now  when  the  terras  are  thus,  there  will  be  nothing  necessary 
inferred,  but  if  B  C  be  converted,  and  B  be  assumed  to  be 
contingent  to  every  C,  a  syllogism  arises  as  before,  since  the 
terms  have  a  similar  position.  In  the  same  man-  4.  Both  pre- 
ner,  when  both  the  propositions  are  negative,  if  A  mises  negative. 
B  signifies  not  being  present,  but  B  C  to  be  contingent  to  no 
individual,  through  these  assumptions  no  necessity  arises,  but 
the  contingent  proposition  being  converted,  there  will  be  a 
syllogism.  Let  A  be  assumed  present  to  no  B,  and  B  contin- 
gent to  no  C,  nothing  necessary  is  inferred  from  these  ;  but 
if  it  is  assumed  that  B  is  contingent  to  every  C,  which  is 
true,  and  the  proposition  A  B  subsists  similarly,  there  will 
be  again  the  same  syllogism.  If  however  B  is  assumed  as 
not  present  with  C,  and  not  that  it  happens  not  to  be  pre- 
sent, there  will  by  no  means  be  a  syllogism,  neither  if  the 
proposition  A  B  be  negative  nor  affirmative  ;  but  let  the  com- 
mon terms  of  necessary  presence  be  "white,"  "animal," 
"snow,"  and  of  non-contingency  "white,"  "ani-  *  Exam  le  (6) 
mal,"  "pitch."  *  It  is  evident,  therefore,  that  when 
terms  are  universal,  and  one  of  the  propositions  is  5-  General  law- 
assumed,  as  simply  de  inesse,  but  the  other  con-  gisms^when"" 
tangent,  when  the  minor  premise  is  assumed  con-   !ninor  premise 

»        '  •»  .  is  contingent, 

tmgent,   a  syllogism  always   arises,  except  that   a  syllogism  is 
sometimes  it  will  be  produced  from  the  proposi-   eitoertoectiy 
tions  themselves,  and  at  other  times  from  the  (con-   or  by  conver- 
tingent)  proposition  being  converted  ;  when,  how- 
ever, each  of  these  occurs,   and  for  what  reason,   we  have 
shown.     But  if  one  proposition  be  assumed  as  universal,  and 
the  other  particular,  when  the  universal  contin-       ^ 

.     ...  ,  .  ,     ,1         .     i         6.  Of  partiou- 

gent  is  joined  to  the  major  extreme,  whether  it  be   larswithar. 
affirmative  or  negative,  but  the  particular  is  a  "nj^rsal 

..,   .  n  major. 

simple  affirmative  de  inesse,  there  will  be  a  perfect 


Something  {  white  is  an  animal 

ssot  every  thing ) 

!  every        \ 
110  \  garment  is  white 

not  every  ) 
l*.  is  necessary  that  no  garment  should  be  an  animal. 


118  auistotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

syllogism,  just  as   when   the  terms  are   universal,  but   the 

demonstration  is  the  same  as  before.     Now  when  the  major  is 

2.  Major  a  or    universal,  simple,  and  not  contingent,  but  the  other 

E  pure.  ^he  niinor)  particular  and  contingent,  if    both 

propositions  be  assumed  affirmative  or  negative,  or  if  one  be 

affirmative  and  the  other  negative,  there  will  always  be  an 

incomplete  syllogism,  except  that  some  will  be  demonstrated 

per  impossibile,  but  others  by  conversion  of  the   contingent 

proposition,  as  in  the  former  cases.     There  will 

also  be  a  syllogism,  through  conversion,  when  the 

universal  major  signifies  simply  inesse,  or  non-inesse,  but  the 

particular  being  negative,  assumes  the  contingent,  as  if  A  is 

present,  or  not  present,  with  every  B,  that  B  happens  not  to 

be  present  with  a  certain  C  ;  for  the  contingent  proposition 

B  C  being  converted,  there  is  a  syllogism.     Still 

when  the  particular  proposition  assumes  the  not 

being  present  with,  there  will  not  be  a  syllogism.     Now  let 

the  terms  of  presence  be  "white,"  "animal,"  "snow,"  but  of 

not  being  present  "white,"  "animal,"  "pitch,"  for  the  demon- 

,   „  .   stration  must  be  assumed  through  the  indefinite.* 

*  Example  (7.)    —,...»,  .  ii«*-iii 

Yet  it  the  universal  be  joined  to  the  less  extreme, 
fs  If  ticuiar^  ^ut  Pai*ticular  to  the  greater,  whether  negative  or 
there  win  be  no  affirmative,  contingent  or  pure,  there  will  by  no 
i7bo°thpremU;es  means  be  a  syllogism,  nor  if  particular  or  inde- 
be  particular      finite  propositions  be  assumed,  whether  they  take 

the  contingent,  or  simply  the  being  present  with, 
or  vice  versa,  will  there  thus  be  a  syllogism,  and  the  demon- 
stration is  the  same  as  before  ;  let  however  the  common  terms 
of  being  present  with  from  necessity  be  "animal,"  "white," 
.  „        .  ...    "man;"  and  of  not  being  contingent  "animal," 

"white,  "garment,  j  Hence  it  is  evident,  that 
if  the  major  be  universal,  there  is  always  a  syllogism,  but  if 
the  minor  be  so,  (if  the  major  be  particular,)  there  will  never  be. 

Chap.  XVI. — Of  Syllogisms  with  one  Premise  necessary,  and  the 
other  contingent  in  the  first  Figure. 

m    ,  When  one  is  a  necessary  proposition  simple,  de 

1.  The  law  re-     .  .  i   .1         fi  •       •„       ,     . 

lative  to  syiio-    inesse,  or  non-inesse,  and  the  other  signifies  being 

character*1"8      contingent,  there  will  be  a  syllogism,  the  terms 

subsisting  similarly,  and  it  will  be  perfect  when 


CHAP. 


XVI.] 


THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS. 


119 


the  minor  premise l  is  necessary  ;  the  conclusion  however,  when 
the  terms  are  affirmative,  will  be  contingent,  and  not  simple, 
whether  they  are  universal  or  not  universal.    Nevertheless,  if 
one  proposition  be  affirmative,  and  the  other  negative,  when 
the  affirmative  is  necessary,  the  conclusion  will  in  like  manner 
signify  the  being  contingent,  and  not  the  not-existing  or  being 
present  with  ;  and  when  the  negative  is  necessary,  the  con- 
clusion will  be  of  the  contingent  non-inesse,  and  of  the  sim- 
ple non-inesse,  whether  the  terms  are  universal  or  not.     The 
contingent  also  in  the  conclusion,  is  to  be  assumed  in  the  same 
way  as  in  the  former  syllogisms,  but  there  will  not  be  a  syllo- 
gism wherein  the  non-inesse  will  be  necessarily  inferred,  for 
it  is  one  thing  "inesse"  not  necessarily,  and  another  "non- 
inesse  "  necessarily.    Wherefore,  it  is  evident  that   2  When  both 
when  the  terms  are  affirmative,  there  will  not  be   premises  are 
a  necessary  conclusion.     For  let  A  necessarily  be   not  bet  neces- 
present  with  every  B,  but  let  B  be  contingent  to   sary  conciu- 
every  C,  there  will  then  be  an  incomplete  syllo- 
gism, whence  it  may  be  inferred  that  A  happens  to  be  present 
with  every  C ;  but  that  it  is  incomplete,  is  evident  from  de- 


1  Major  premise  r)  7rpoc  r<f>  (itiZ,ovi 
iXarrovi.  dfcpy  Tvporauig.  Conclusion 
this  last  signifies  also  the  minor  term. 

Ex.  1.  It   is   necessary    that  no    B 
should  be  A 
It  happens  that  every  C  is  B 
.  • .  No  C  is  A. 

Ex.  2.  It  happens  that  j  ^      ^  >  ani- 
mal is  white 
It  is  necessary  that  no  snow 

should  be  an  animal 
It  is  necessary  that  all  snow 
should  be  white. 

Ex.  3.   It  is  necessary  that  something 
white    should 
animal 
It  happens  that  \        M  man 


aKpy  TrporaoiQ — minor  >/  irpoq  ry> 
0-vniripa.Gp.a.     In  Anal.  Pr.  ii.  14, 

It  is  necessary  that  no  A  should 

be  B 
Some  C  is  A 
.  •  .   It  is  necessary  that  some  C 
should  not  be  B. 


( not  be  j 


an 


no       J 

is  white 
It  is  necessary  that  every  man 

should  be  an  animal. 


It  happens  that  j         '  >  animal  is 

white 
It  is  necessary  that  no  pitch  should 

be  an  animal 
It  is  necessary  that  no  pitch  should 

be  white. 

1 1  is  necessary  that  something  white 
should{notbe}ananimal 

It  happens  that  <   ver^  £  garment 

is  white 
It   is  necessary   that  no   garment 
should  be  an  animal. 


120  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

monstration,  for  this  may  be  shown  after  the  same  manner  as 
in  the  former  syllogisms.  Again,  let  A. he  contingent  to 
every  B,  but  let  B  be  necessarily  present  with  every  C,  there 
will  then  be  a  syllogism  wherein  A  happens  to  be  present  with 
every  C,  but  not  (simply)  is  it  present  with  every  C,  also  it  will 
be  complete,  and  not  incomplete,  for  it  is  completed  by  the  first 
i.  Negative  propositions.  Notwithstanding,  if  the  propositions 
necessary.  are  not  0f  similar  form,  first,  let  the  negative  one 
be  necessary,  and  let  A  necessarily  be  contingent  to  no  B,  but. 
let  B  be  contingent  to  every  C ;  therefore,  it  is  necessary  that 
A  should  be  present  with  no  C  ;  for  let  it  be  assumed  present, 
either  with  every  or  with  some  one,  yet  it  was  supposed  to 
be  contingent  to  no  B.  Since  then  a  negative  proposition  is 
convertible,  neither  will  B  be  contingent  to  any  A,  but  A  is 
supposed  to  be  present  with  every  or  with  some  C,  hence  B 
will  happen  to  be  present  with  no,  or  not  with  every  C,  it 
,  ,, ,    was  however  supposed,  from  the  first,  to  be  pre- 

*  Example  (1.)  .  ,  \A  *.     n  «n  ■     •  .  -i  ,  . 

sent  with  every  C*  Still  it  is  evident,  that  there 
may  also  be  a  syllogism  of  the  contingent  non-inesse,  as  there 

2.  Affirmative  is  one  of  the  simple  non-inesse.  Moreover,  let 
necessary.  ^g  affirmative  proposition  be  necessary,  and  let 
A  be  contingently  present  with  no  B,  but  B  necessarily  pre- 
sent with  every  C :  this  syllogism  then  will  be  perfect,  yet 
not  of  the  simple,  but  of  the  contingent  non-inesse,  for  the 
proposition  (viz.  the  contingent  non-inesse)  was  assumed  from 
the  major  extreme,  and  there  cannot  be  a  deduction  to  the 
impossible,  for  if  A  is  supposed  to  be  present  with  a  certain 
C,  and  it  is  admitted  that  A  is  contingently  present  with  no 
B,  nothing  impossible  will  arise  therefrom.     But  if  the  minor 

3.  Minor  nega-  premise  be  negative  when  it  is  contingent,  there 
tive  contingent.  wiu  De  a  syllogism  by  conversion,  as  in  the  former 
cases,  but  when  it  is  not  contingent,  there  will  not  be ;  nor 
when  both  premises  are  negative,  but  the  minor  not  contin- 
gent :  let  the  terms  be  the  same  of  the  simple  inesse  "  white,'' 

"animal,"  "snow," and  of  the  non-inesse  "white," 

"animal,"  "pitch."f 
The  same  will  also  happen  in  particular  syllogisms,  for  when 

the  negative  is  necessary,  the  conclusion  will  be  of 
ticuiaresyiio-ar"  the  simple  non-inesse.  Thus  if  A  is  contingently 
gisms.  present  with  no  B,  but  B  contingently  present  with 

a  certain  C,  it  is  necessary  that  A  should  not  be 


t  Example  (2.)    ,  ,  „  u 


CHAP.  XVI.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  12) 

present  with  a  certain  C.  since  if  it  is  present  with  every  C,  but 
is  contingent  to  no  B,  neither  will  B  be  contingently  pres:  nt 
with  any  A.     So  that  if  A  is  present  with  every  C,  B  is  ci  n- 
tingent  with  no  C,  but  it  was  supposed  contingent  to  a  cer- 
tain C.     When  however  in  a  negative  syllogism  the  particular 
affirmative  is  necessary,  as  for  example  B  C,  or 
the  universal  in  an  affirmative  syllogism,  e.  g.  A 
B,   there    will   not    be   a    syllogism    tie   inesse,   the   demon- 
stration however  is  the  same  as  in  the  former  cases.     But  if 
the  minor  premise  be  universal,  Avhether  affirm- 
ative or  negative  and  contingent,  but  the  major 
particular  necessary,  there  will  not  be  a  syllogism,  let  the 
terms  of  necessary  presence  be  "  animal,"  "  white,"  "  man," 
and  of  the   non-contingent   "  animal,"    "  white,"    „  ^        ,    „ , 

»*.       -r.  11  •  •  *  Example  (3.) 

"  garment.   *     But  when  the  universal  is  neces- 
sary, and  the  particular  contingent,  the  universal  being  nega- 
tive,   let    the   terms   of   presence1    be    "animal,"    "white," 
"crow,"  and  of  non-inesse  "animal,"   "white,"    .  r        ,  ,, . 

"  pitch."  f  t  Example  (4, 

But  when  (the  universal)  affirms  let  the  terms 

of  presence  be  "  animal,"  "  white,"  "  swan,'"'  but  4- 

of  the   non-contingent   be    "animal,"    "white,"  j  Example (5.) 

"  snow."  J     Nor  will  there  be  a  syllogism  when  in-  4  Case  of  both 

definite  propositions  are  assumed  or  both  particular,  premises  inde- 

let  the   common   terms,  de  inesse,  be  "animal,"  cuiar.°r pam" 
"  white,"  "  man,"  de  non-inesse  "  animal,"  "  white," 
"  inanimate  ;"  for  "  animal "  is  necessarily  and  not  contingently 

'  That  is,  of  the  major  being  with  the  minor. 

Ex.  4.   It   happens    that    something     It  happens  that  something  white 

white  {  !s       .  \  an  animal  |  .        .  \  an  animal 

( is  not)  { is  not) 

It  is  necessary  that  no  crow  It  is  necessary  that  no  pitch  should 

should  be  white  be  white 

It  is  necessary  that  every  crow  It  is  necessary  that  no  pitch  should 

should  be  an  animal.  be  an  animal. 

Ex.  5.  It  happens    that    something     It  happens  that  something  white 

white  I  •'       .  /  an  animal  <  .'       .  J  an  animal 

( is  not )  (is  not ) 

I L  is  necessary  that  every  swan  It  is  necessary  that  all  snow  should 

should  be  white  be  white 

It  is  necessary  that  every  swan  It  is  necessary  that  no  snow  should 

shou!'!  be  an  anirr-d.  be  an  animal 


122  Aristotle's  org  anon.  [book  i. 

present  with  something  "  white,"  and  "  white  "  is  also  neces- 
sarily and  not  contingently  present  with  something  "  inani- 

*  Exam  i  (6i    mate »"  tne  ^^e  a^so  occurs  in  the  contingent,  so 
that  these  terms  are  useful  for  all.* 
From  what  has  been  said  then  it  appears  that  when  the 
terms  are  alike  both  in  simple  and  in  necessary  propositions, 
5.  conclusion     a  syllogism  does  and  does  not  occur,  except  that 
from  the  above,   if  the  negative  proposition  be  assumed  de  inesse 
there  will  be  a  syllogism  with  a  contingent  (con- 
clusion), but  when  the  negative  is  necessary  there  will  be  one 
of  the  character  of  the  contingent  and  of  the  non-inesse,  but 
it  is  clear  also  that  all  the  syllogisms  are  incomplete,1  and  that 
they  are  completed  through  the  above-named  figures. 

Chap.  XVII. —  Of  Syllogisms  ivith  tico  contingent  Premises  in  the 

second  Figure. 

.  _  ,  ,  In  the  second  figure,  when  both  premises  are  as- 

1.  Ruleforcon-  ,  .  ,  .,,  ,  l        ,, 

titigent  syiio-  sumed  contingent,  there  will  be  no  syllogism,  nei- 
fg™  in  thls  ther  when  they  are  taken  as  affirmative,  nor  nega- 
tive, nor  universal,  nor  particular;  but  when, one 
signifies  the  simple  inesse,  and  the  other  the  contingent,  if  the 
affirmative  signifies  the  inesse,  there  will  never  be  a  syllogism, 
but  if  the  universal  negative  (be  pure,  there  will)  always  (be  a 

Ex.  6.  It    happens    that  something;     It  happens  that  something  white 

white  |  .  1  an  animal  ]  -S      ,  >  an  animal 

( is  not )  \  is  not ) 

It  is  necessary  that  some  man     It  is  necessary  that  something  in- 

should  \        ,     J  white  animate  should  <    e    ,     >  white 

It  is  necessary  that  every  man     It  is  necessary  that  nothing  inani- 
should  be  an  animal.  mate  should  be  an  animal. 

It  is  necessary  that  something     It  is  necessary  that  something  white 

white  should  \      .  ,     !  an         should  {    e.  ,     >  an  animal 
(  not  be  j  I  not  be  ) 

animal 

It  happens    that  some    man     It  happens  that  every  thing  inani- 

( is         )      ,..  mate  is  white 

{  ■        ..}  white 
(  is  not ) 

It  is  necessary  that  every  man     It  is  necessary  that  nothing  inani- 

should  be  an  animal.  mate  should  be  an  animal. 

1  Those  are  syllogisms  with  a  contingent  minor,  but  a  necessary  or 
fure  maji> 


CHAP.  XVII.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  123 

syllogism).    In  the  same  manner,  when  one  premise  is  assumed 
as  necessary,  but  the  other  contingent  ;  still  in  these  syllogisms 
we  must  consider  the  contingent  in  the  conclusions, 
as  we  did  in  the  former  ones.  Now  in  the  first  place,   contingent  ne- 
we  must  show  that  a  contingent  negative  is  not  con-   &atiTe ,not  con_ 

to  b  -!-.••  vertible. 

vertible,  e.  g.  if  A  is  contingent  to  no  B,  it  is  not 
necessary  that  B  should  also  be  contingent  to  no  A.  For  let  this 
be  assumed,  and  let  B  be  contingently  present  with  no  A,  there- 
fore since  contingent  affirmatives,  both  contrary  and  contra- 
dictory, are  convertible  into  negatives,  and  B  is  contingently 
present  with  no  A,  it  is  clear  that  B  may  be  contingently 
present  with  every  A ;   but  this  is  false,  for  if 
this  is  contingent  to  all  of  that,  it  is  not  necessary 
that  that  should  be  contingent  to  this,  wherefore  a  negative 
(contingent)  is  not  convertible.     Moreover,  there  is  nothing 
to  prevent  A  being  contingent  to  no  B,  but  B  not  necessarily 
present  with  a  certain  A,  e.  g.  "whiteness"  may  happen  not 
to  be  present  with  every  "  man,"  (for  it  may  also  happen)  to 
be  present ;  but  it  is  not  true  to  say,  that  man  is  contingently 
present  with  nothing  "  white,"  for  he  is  necessarily  not  pre- 
sent with  many  things  (white),  and  the  necessary  is  not  the 
contingent.     Neither  can  it  be  shown  convertible  per  impos- 
sibile,  as  if  a  man  should  think,  since  it  is  false  that  B  is  con- 
tingently present  with  no  A,  that  it  is  true  that  it 
(A)  is  not  contingent  to  no  one  (B),  for  these  are 
affirmation  and  negation  ;  but  if  this  be  true  B  is  necessarily 
present  with  a  certain  A,  therefore  A  is  also  with  a  certain  B, 
but  this  is  impossible,  since  it  does  not  follow  if  B  is  not  con- 
tingent to  no  A,  that  it  is  necessarily  present  with  a  certain  A. 
For  not  to  be  contingent  to  no  individual,  is  pre- 
dicated two  ways,  the  one  if  a  thing  is  necessarily  preheated  neC-y 
present  with  something,  and    the  other  if  it  is   gatively  in  two 

1  .,  .  ,  ,  .  -n  i  ways — the  cha- 

necessanly  not  present  with  something,    t  or  what   racter  of  the 
necessarily  is  not  present  with  a  certain  A,  can-   opposi,^1 
not  be  truly  said  to  be  contingently  not  present 
with  every  A ;  as  neither  can  what    is  necessarily  present 
with  a  certain  thing,  be  truly  said  to  be  contingently  present 
with  every  thing ;  if,  then,  any  one  thinks  that  because  C  is 
not  contingently  present  with  every  D,  it  is  necessarily  not 
present  with  a  certain   D,  he  would  infer  falsely,  for,  per- 
chance, it  is  present  with  every  D  ;   still  because  a  thing  is 


124  Aristotle's  org  axon.  [book  l 

necessarily  present  with  certain  things,  on  this  account,  we 
say  that  it  is  not  contingent  to  every  individual.  Wherefore 
the  being  present  necessarily  with  a  certain  thing,  and  the 
not  being  present  with  a  certain  thing  necessarily,  are  op- 
posed to  the  being  contingently  present  with  every  individual, 
and  in  like  manner,  there  is  a  similar  opposition  to  the  being 
contingent  to  no  individual.  Hence  it  is  evident,  that  when 
the  contingent  and  non-contingent  are  taken,  in  the  manner 
we  first  defined,  not  only  the  necessarily  being  present  with 
a  certain  thing,  but  also  the  necessarily  not  being  present 
with  it,  ought  to  be  assumed  ;  but  when  this  is  assumed,  there 
is  no  impossibility  to  a  syllogism  being  produced,  whence  it 
is  evident,  from  what  we  have  stated,  that  a  negative  con- 
tingent is  not  convertible. 

4.  From  two  This  then   being  demonstrated,  let  A  be  as- 

pwamseBTini-  sume(|  contingent  to  no  B,  but  contingent  to 
(E)  contingent  every  C  ;  by  conversion,  therefore,  there  will  not 
figure,  mfsyiio-  De  a  syllogism,  for  it  has  been  said  that  a  proposi- 
gis™  is  con-       tion  of  this  kind  is  inconvertible,  neither,  however, 

strutted  « 

will  there  be  by  a  deduction  per  impossibile.    For 

B  being  assumed  contingently  present  with  every  C,  nothing 

false  will  happen,  for  A  may  contingently  be  present  with 

_        ,  .,  .    every,  and  with  no  C* '     In  short,  if  there  is  a 

*  Example  (1.)         ,,       .  ...  .         ...  ,       '„ 

syllogism,  it  is  clear  that  it  will  be  ol  the  contin- 
gent, (because  neither  proposition  is  assumed  as  de  inesse,) 
and  this  either  affirmative,  or  negative ;  it  is  possible,  how- 
ever, in  neither  way,  since,  if  the  affirmative  be  assumed,  it 
can  be  shown  by  the  terms,  that  it  is  not  contingently  present ; 
but  if  the  negative,  that  the  conclusion  is  not  contingent,  but 
necessary.  For  let  A  be  "white,"  B  "man,"  and  C  "horse,"  A 
therefore,  i.  e.  "whiteness,"  is  contingently  present  with  every 
individual  of  the  one,  though  with  no  individual  of  the  other, 

1  Ex.  1.  It  happens  that  no  B  is  A  It  happens  that  no  B  is  A 

It  happens  that  every  C  is  A  It  is  necessary  that  every  or 

some  C  should  be  B 
. '  .    It  happens  that  no  C  is  B.  .  • .  It  happens  that  every  or  some 

C  is  not  A. 

I  have  followed  Waitz  here.     Buhle  reads  the  letters  and  statement  of 
premises  differently. 

Ex.  2.   It  happens  that  no  man  is  white 

It  happens  that  every  horse  is  white 

It  is  necessary  that  no  horse  should  be  a  man. 


CHAP.  XVIII.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS. 


125 


but  B  is  neither  contingently  present,  nor   yet  contingently 
not  present,  with  C.     It  is  evident  that  it  is  not  contingently 
present,  for  no  "horse"  is  "a  man,"  but  neither  does  it  hap- 
pen not  to  be  present,  for  it  is  necessary  that  no  "  horse " 
should  be  "a  man,"  and  the  necessary  is  not  the   t 
contingent,  wherefore  there  is  no  syllogism.*  This 
may  be  also  similarly  shown,  if  the  negative  be  transposed,1 
and  if  both  propositions  be  assumed  affirmative, 
or  negative,  for  the  demonstration  will  be  by  the 
same  terms.']'     When  one  proposition  also  is  uni-   5-  Norfromone 
versal,  but  the  other  particular,  or  both  particular   other  par.,  or6 
or  indefinite,  or  in  whatever  other  way  it  is  pos-   both  pm-  orln 
sible  to  change  the  propositions,  for  the  demon- 
stration will  always  be  through  the  same  terms. J   *  ExaraPle  (*•' 
Hence  it  is  clear  that  if  both  propositions  are  as- 
sumed contingent  there  is  no  syllogism.2 


ure, 
with  one  pu  b 
premise,  aiil 


Chap.    XVIII. —  Of  Syllogisms  with  one  Proposition  simple,  and  the 
other  contingent,  in  the  second  Figure. 

If  one  proposition  signifies  inesse,  but  the  other   1.  Rule  for 
the  contingent,  the  affirmative  proposition  being   ""^fig311 
simple,   but  the  negative  contingent,  there   will 
never  be  a  syllogism,  neither  if  the  terms  be  as- 

1  i.  e.  If  the  major  affirm,  and  the  minor  deny. 

Ex.  3.  It  happens  that  j    V       }  man  is  white 

It  happens  that  |         M  horse  is  white 
It  is  necessarv  that  no  horse  should  be  a  man. 


Ex 


4.  It  happens  that  (  every  )  man     II  happens  that  some  man 

*no  (Is      J  white 

( is  not  J 


is  white 


It  happens  that  some  horse     j     h  ^  {  every  j  ho^[a 

!s      J  white  *  U°      > 

{ is  not  j  white 

It  is  necessary  that  no  horse     It  is  necessary  that  no  horse  should 
should  be  a  man.  be  a  man. 

It  happens  that  some  man  { •        ,  }  white 

It  happens  that  some  horse  |  • ,      .  |  white 
It  is  necessary  that  no  horse  should  be  a  man. 
•  The  last  sentence  is  omitted  by  Taylor. 


126 


ARISTOTLE  S    ORGANON. 


[book 


the  other  con-  sumed  universally,  or  partially,  still  the  demon- 
stration will  be  the  same,  and  by  the  same  terms, 
yet  when  the  affirmative  is  contingent,  but  the  negative  sim- 
ple, there  will  be  a  syllogism.  For  let  A  be  assumed  present 
with  no  B,  but  contingent  with  every  C,  then  by 
conversion  of  the  negative,  B  will  be  present  with 
no  A,  but  A  is  contingent  to  every  C,  therefore  there  is  a 
syllogism  in  the  first  figure,  that  B  is  contingent  to  no  C. 
So  also  if  the  negative  be  added  to  C  ;  but  if  both  propositions 
be  negative,  and  one  signifies  the  simple,  but  the  other  the 
contingent  non-inesse,  from  these  assumed  propositions  nothing 
necessary  is  inferred,  but  the  contingent  proposition  being 
converted,1  there  is  a  syllogism,  wherein  B  is  contingently 
present  with  no  C,  as  in  the  former,  for  again  there  will  be 
the  first  figure.     If,  however,  both  propositions  be  assumed 


1  If  the  contingent  negative  proposition  be  changed  into  an  affirmative. 


Ex.  1.  It  happens  that  every  animal 

is  well 
Every  man  is  well 
It  is  necessary  that  every  man 

should  be  an  animal. 

Every  animal  is  well 

It  happens  that  every  man  is 

well 
It  is  necessary  that  every  man 

should  be  an  animal. 

Ex.  2.  It  happens  that  no  animal  is 

well 
Some  man  is  well 
It  is  necessary  that  every  man 

should  be  an  animal. 

Every  animal  is  well 

It  happens  that  some  man  is 

not  well 
It  is  necessary  that  every  man 

should  be  an  animal. 


Ex.  3    Some  animal 


iis        ) 

( is  not ) 


well 


is 

is  not 
It  happens  that  some   man 


{»      Jwell 

I  is  not ) 


It  is  necessary  that  every  man 
should  be  an  ariaal. 


It  happens  that  every  horse  is  well 

Every  man  is  well 
It  is  necessary  that  no  man  should 
be  a  horse. 

Every  horse  is  well 

It  happens  that  every  man  is  well 

It  is  necessary  that  no  man  should 
be  a  horse. 

It  happens  that  no  horse  is  well 

Some  man  is  well 
It  is  necessary  that  no  man  should 
be  a  horse. 

Every  horse  is  well 

It  happens  that  some  man  is  not 

well 
It  is  necessary  that  no  man  should 

be  a  horse. 

Some  horse  \  .        .  f  well 
( is  not ) 

It  happens    that  some   man 

f-S      .Nell 
( is  not  J 

It  is  necessary  that  no  man  should 

be  ahorse. 


CHAP.  XIX.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  127 

affirmative,  there  will  not  be  a  syllogism  :  let  the 

terms  of  presence  be  "health,"  "animal,"  "man," 

but  of  not  being  present  with  "  health,"  "  horse," 

"  man."*     The  same  will  happen  in  the  case  of  e  v 

particular  syllogisms,  for  when  the  affirmative  is 

pure,   taken   either  universally,   or  particularly,   fylwfsm"lar 

there   will  be  no  syllogism,   and  this   is  shown 

in  like  manner  through  the  same  terms  as   be-    ,  ^        ,  ,„ , 

r  .        -r.  ,  ,    °  .....  t  Example  (2.) 

tore.y  .But  when  the  negative  is  simple,  there 
will  be  a  syllogism  by  conversion,  as  in  the  former  cases. 
Again,  if  both  premises  be  taken  negative,  and  that  which  signi- 
fies simply  the  non-inesse  be  universal ;  from  these  propositions 
no  necessity  will  result,  but  the  contingent  being  converted  as 
before  there  will  be  a  syllogism.  If  however  the  negative 
be  pure  but  particular,  there  will  not  be  a  syllogism,  whether 
the  other  premise  be  affirmative  or  negative.  Neither  will 
there  be  one,  when  both  propositions  are  assumed  indefinite, 
whether  affirmative,  negative,  or  particular,  and  the    .  _        ,  ,„, 

.  .         .  '       °  tit  <      t  Example  (3.) 

demonstration  is  the  same  and  by  the  same  terms.| 

Chap.  XIX. — Of  Syllogisms  with  one  Premise  necessary  and  the 
other  contingent,  in  the  second  Figure. 

If  however  one  premise  signifies  the  being  present  ,   Rule  in 

necessarily,  but  the  other  contingently,  when  the  these  when  the 

negative  is  necessary  there  will  be  a  syllogism,  mlfe  is  neces- 

wherein  not  only  the  contingent  but  also  the  simple  sary'  a  syll°" 

r      i    •  t>      I-,       i       i     «■         £ism  may bc 

non-inesse  (may  be  inferred),  but  when  the  amrma-  constructed. 
tive  (is  necessary)  there  will  be  no  syllogism.  For  '"  Case" 
let  A  be  assumed  necessarily  present  with  no  B,  but  contingent 
to  every  C,  then  by  conversion  of  the  negative  neither  will  B  be 
present  with  any  A,  but  A  was  contingent  to  every  C,  wherefore 
there  is  again  a  syllogism  in  the  first  figure,  so  that  B  is  con- 
tingently present  with  no  C.  At  the  same  time  it  is  shown  that 
neither  is  B  present  with  any  C,  for  let  it  be  assumed  to  be 

It  happens  that  some  animal     It  happens   that   some   horse 

?s      ,lwell  jis      J  well 

I  is  not )  \  is  not  j 

Some   man   .  •'       A  well  Some    man  { .       .  J  well 

I  is  not )  \  is  not ) 

It  is  necessary  that  every  man     It  is  necessary  that  no  man  should 

should  be  an  animal  be  a  horse. 


128  Aristotle's  organon.  ("book  i 

present,  therefore  if  A  is  contingent  to  no  B,  but  B  is  present 
with  a  certain  C,  A  is  not  contingent  to  a  certain  C,  but  it 
was  supposed  contingent  to  every  C,  and  it  may  be  shown 
after  the  same  manner,  if  the  negative  be  added  to  C.  Again, 
2  Caseofane-  ^et  tne  affirmative  proposition  be  necessary,  but 
cessary  affirm-    the  other  negative  and  contingent,  and  let  A  be 

contingent  to  no  B,  but  necessarily  present  with 
every  C  ;  now  when  th<=».  terms  are  thus,  there  will  be  no  syl- 
logism, for  it  may  happen  that  B  is  necessarily  not  present 
with  C.  Let  A  be  "  white,"  B  "  man,"  C  "  a  swan  ;"  "  white- 
ness," then,  is  necessarily  present  with  "  a  swan,"  but  is  con- 
tingent to  no  "  man,"  and  "  man  "  is  necessarily  present  with 
no  "swan  ;"  therefore  that  there  will  be  no  syllogism  of  the 
*  f  contingent  is  palpable,  for  what  is  necessary  is  not 

contingent.*  '  Yet  neither  will  there  be  a  syllogism 
of  the  necessary,  for  the  latter  is  either  inferred  from  two  ne- 
cessary premises,  or  from  a  negative  (necessary  premise)  ;  be- 
sides, from  these  data  it  follows  that  B  may  be  present  with 
C,  for  there  is  nothing  to  prevent  C  from  being  under  B,  and 
A  from  being  contingent  to  every  B,  and  necessarily  present 
with  C,  as  if  C  is  "awake,"  B  "  aniftial,"  and  A  "motion;" 
for  "  motion  "  is  necessarily  present  with  whatever  is  "  awake," 
but  contingent  to  every  "  animal,"  and  every  thing  which  is 
.,„.■"  awake "  is   "  an  animal."!     Hence  it  appears 

+  Example  (2.)  .  .  . '  .    „  -,•■„, 

that  neither  the  non-inesse  is  interred,  since  if  the 
terms  are  thus  the  inesse  is  necessary,  nor  when  the  enunci- 
ations are  opposite,2  so  that  there  will  be  no  syllogism.     There 

1  Ex.  1.  It  happens  that  no  man  is  white 

It  is  necessary  that  every  swan  should  be  white 
It  is  necessary  that  no  swan  should  be  a  man. 

Ex.  2.   It  happens  that  no  animal  is  moved 

It  is  necessary  that  every  thing  awake  should  be  moved 
Every  thing  awake  is  an  animal. 

Alexander  Aphrodisiensis  observes  that  the  example  would  be  clearer, 
.f  "  walking  "  were  assumed  instead  of  "  awake."  because  it  is  more  ob- 
viously necessary  that  a  thing  which  walks  should  be  "  moved,"  than  a 
thing  which  is  awake. 

'  "  Will  there  be  a  syllogism  from  such  propositions  " — there  is  an  el- 
lipse of  these  words  here.  The  case  is  that  neither  a  contingent  nor  ne- 
cessary affirmation  is  to  be  inferred,  since  sometimes  the  non-inesse  is 
necessary. 


CHAP.  XIX.] 


THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS. 


129 


3.  Case  of  hcth 
negative. 


will  be  also  a  similar  demonstration  if  the  affirm- 
ative premise  be  transposed,  but  if  the  proposi- 
tions are  of  the  same  character,  when  they  are 
negative,  a  syllogism  is  always  formed,  the  contingent  pro- 
position being  converted,  as  in  the  former  cases.  For  let  A 
be  assumed  necessarily  not  present  with  B,  and  contingently 
not  present  with  C,  then  the  propositions  being  converted,  B 

Ex.  3.  It  is  necessary  that  every  swan  should  be  w,hite 
It  happens  that  every  man  is  white 
It  is  necessary  that  no  man  should  be  a  swan. 
Ex.  4.  It  happens  that  no  man  is     It  happens  that  no  animal  is  moved 
white 
It  is  necessary  that  some  swan 

should  be  white 
It  is  necessary  that  no  swan 
should  be  a  man. 
It  is  necessary  that  every  swan  should  be  white 
It  happens  that  some  man  is  not  white 
It  is  necessary  that  no  man  should  be  a  swan. 
Ex.  5.  It   is  necessary   that    every     It  happens  that  every  man  is  white 


It  is  necessary  that  something 
awake  should  be  moved 

It  is  necessary  that  every  thing 
awake  should  be  an  animal. 


swan  should  be  white 
It  happens  that  some  man  is 

a  swan 
It  is  necessary  that  no  man 

should  be  a  swan. 

It  is  necessary  that  some  swan 

should  be  white 
It  happens  that  every  man  is 

white 
It  is  necessary  that  no  man 

should  be  a  swan. 

Ex.  6.   It  happens  that  some  animal 

ilS      A  white 
{ is  not  J 

It  is  necessary  that  some  man 

(bef,     |  white 
(  not  be  j 

It  is  necessary  that  every  man 

should  be  an  animal 

It  is  necessary  that  some  ani. 

mal  should  j^tbe}  white 

It  happens  that   some   man 

| 1S      ,1  white 
( is  not ) 

It  is  necessary  that  every  man 

should  be  an  animal 


shouk 


It  is   necessary  that  some  swan 

should  be  white 
It  is  necessary  that  no  swan  should 

be  a  man. 

It  happens  that  some  man  is  white 

It  is  necessary   that  every   swan 

should  be  white 
It  is  necessary  that  no  swan  should 

be  a  man. 

It  happens  that  some  animal 

I  ■        .  >  white 
( is  not ) 

It  is  necessary  that  something  in- 
animate should  |      ,  ,     >  white 
{  not  be  ) 

It   is   necessary  that   nothing   in- 
animate should  be  an  animal. 

It  is  necessary  that  some  animal 

should  ]      .  ,     1  white 
( not  be ) 

It    happens    that   something    in- 
animate \  h      .  >  white 
I  is  not  \ 

It  is  necessary   that  nothing  in- 
animai e  should  be  an  animal. 


130  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

is  present  with  no  A,  and  A  is  contingent  with  every  C,  and 
the  first  figure  is  produced  ;  the  same  would  also  occur  if  the 
negation  belongs  to  C.     But  if  both  propositions  be  affirma- 
tive, there  will  not  be  a  syllogism,  clearly  not  of 

4.  Case  of  both     .,'  e  vu  • 

affirmative.        the  non-inesse,  nor  ot  the  necessary  non-inesse, 
because  a  negative  premise  is  not  assumed,  nei- 
ther in  the  simple,  nor  in  the  necessary  inesse.     Neither, 
again,    will  there  be    a   syllogism   of   the    contingent    non- 
inesse,  for  necessary  terms  being  assumed,  B  will  not  be  pre- 
sent with  C,  e.  g.  if  A  be  assumed  "  white,"  B  "  a  swan,"  and 
C  "man  ;"  nor  will  there  be  from  opposite  affirmations,  since 
B  has  been  shown  necessarily  not  present  with  C,  in  short, 
*  e       1         therefore,  a  syllogism  will  not  be  produced.*     It 
will  happen  the  same  in  particular  syllogisms,  for 
when  the  negative  is  universal  and  necessary, 
syllogisms.         there  will  always  be  a  syllogism  of  the  contingent, 
and  of  the  non-inesse,  but  the  demonstration  will 
be  by  conversion  ;  still,  when  the  affirmative  (is  necessary), 
there  will  never  be  a  syllogism,  and  this  may  be  shown  in 
.  _        .   .. ,    the  same  way  as  in  the  universals,  and  by  the 

t  Example  (4.)  J  '  .  J 

same  terms. j  JNor  when  both  premises  are  as- 
i  Example  (5 )    sume<^  affirmative,  for  of  this  there   is  the  same 

demonstration  as  before,^:  but  when  both  are  ne- 
gative, and  that  which  signifies  the  non-inesse  is  universal, 
and  necessary ;  the  necessary  will  not  be  concluded  through 
the  propositions,  but  the  contingent  being  converted,  there 
will  be  a  syllogism  as  before.  If  however  both  propositions  are 
laid  down  indefinite,  or  particular,  there  will  not  be  a  syllogism, 
§  Example  (6 )  anc^  the  demonstration  is  the  same,  and  by  the 

same  terms.  § 

It  appears  then,  from  what  we  have  said,  that  an  universal, 

and   necessary   negative   being    assumed,  there  is  always  a 

syllogism,  not  only  of  the  contingent,  but  also  of  the  simple 

3  conclusion     non-inesse  ;  but  with  a  necessary  affirmative,  there 

;cf.  cap.  is.)     wiH  never  be  a  syllogism  ;   also  that  when  the 

terms  subsist  in  the  same  manner,  in  necessary, 
as  in  simple  propositions,  there  is,  and  is  not,  a  syllogism  ; 
lastly,  that  all  these  syllogisms  are  incomplete,  and  that  they 
are  completed  through  the  above-mentioned  figures.1 

1  Although  all  incomplete   syllogisms  are  completed  through  the  first 
figure,  yet  some  are,  after  a  manner,  rendered  more  useful  through  another 


CHAP.  XX.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  13  i 


Chap.  XX. —  Of  Syllogisms  icith  both  Propositions  contingent 
in  the  third  Figure. 

In  the  last  figure,  when  both  premises  are  contin- 
gent, and  when  only  one  is  contingent,  there  will   ruieXr  propo- 
be  a  syllogism,  therefore  when  the  premises  sig-   sjtions  of  this 
nify  the  contingent,  the   conclusion   will  also  be 
contingent ;  also  if  one  premise  signifies  the  contingent,  but 
the  other,  the  simple  inesse.     Still  when  one  premise  is  as- 
sumed necessary,  if  it  be  affirmative,  there  will  not  be  a  conclu- 
sion either  necesssry  or  simple,  if  on  the  contrary  it  is  nega- 
tive, there  will  be  a  syllogism  of  the  simple  non-inesse  as  be- 
fore ;  in  these  however  the  contingent  must  be  similarly  taken 
in  the  conclusions.     First  then  let  the  premises    ,    Both 
be  contingent,  and  let  A  and  B  be  contingently   mises  contin- 
present  with  every  C  ;  since  therefore  a  particular   gem 
affirmative  is   convertible,  but   B  is  contingent  to  every  C, 
C  will  also  be  contingent  to  a  certain  B,  therefore  if  A  is  con- 
tingent to  every  C,  but  C  is  contingent  to  a  certain  B,  it  is 
necessary  also  that  A  should  be  contingent  to  a  certain  B,  for 
the  first  figure  is  produced.     If  again  A  is  con- 
tingently present  with  no  C,  but  B  with  every  C, 
A  must  also  of  necessity  be  contingently  not  present  with  a 
certain  B,  for  again  there  will  be  the  first  figure  by  conver- 
sion ; i  but  if  both  propositions  be  assumed  negative  from  these 
the  necessary  will  not  result,  but  the  propositions 
being  converted  there  will  be  a  syllogism  as  be- 
fore.    For  if  A  and  B  are  contingently  not  present  with  C, 

figure,  as  by  changing  the  contingent  affirmative  proposition  into  thb 
negative. 

1  That  is,  by  conversion  of  the  minor. 

Ex.  1.  It  happens  that  something  white  j 1S         [  an  animal 

It  happens  that  something  white  \  .'       ,1a  man 
rr  I  is  not  J 

It  is  necessary  that  every  man  should  be  an  animal 

It  happens  that  something  white     -b         j  a  horse 

It  happens  that  something  white  ,     a  man 

rr  ( is  not ) 

It  is  necessary  that  no  man  should  be  a  horse. 

it  '2 


132  Aristotle's  okganon.  [book  i. 

if  the  contingently  not  present  be  changed,  there  will  again  be 
the  first  figure  by  conversion.     If  however  one 
unWersaiand6   term  De  universal  but  the  other  particular,  when 
the  other  par-     they  are  so,  as  in  the  case  of  simple  inesse,  there 
will,  and  will  not,  be  a  syllogism ;  for  let  A  be 
contingently   present  with    every  C,   and    B   present   with 
a   certain  C,   there  will  again  be   the   first  figure  by  con- 
version of  the  particular  proposition,  since  if  A  is  contingent 
to  every  C,  and  C  to  a  certain  B,  A  is  also  contingent  to  a 
certain  B,  and  in  like  manner  if  the  universal  be  joined  to  B 
C.     This  also  will  be  produced  in  a  similar  way 
if  A  C  be  negative,  but  B  C  affirmative,  for  again 
we  shall  have  the  first  figure  by  conversion,  if  however  both 
are  negative,  the  one  universal  and  the  other  particular,  by 
the  assumed  propositions  there  will  not  be  a  syllogism,  but 
6.  Both  parti-     there  will  be  when  they  are  converted  as  before. 
cuiar  or  indeii-    Lastly,  when  both  are  indefinite   or    particular, 
there  will  not  be  a  syllogism,  for  A  must  neces- 
sarily be  present  with  every  and  with  no  B,  let  the  terms 
de   inesse  be    "animal,"    "man,"    "white,"   and  de  non-in- 
,  „  ,   esse  "horse,"  "man,"  "white,"  the  middle  term 

«  Example  (1.)    My^^nm 


Chap.  XXI. —  Of  Syllogisms  with  one  Proposition  contingent  and 
the  other  simple  in  the  third  Figure. 

l.  Rule  of  con-  ^F  however  one  premise  signifies  the  inesse,  but 
sequence— a  the  other  the  contingent,  the  conclusion  will  be 
Inferred  from  that  a  thing  is  contingent  to,  and  not  that  it  is 
ami  another  present  with  (another),  and  there  will  be  a  syllo- 
contingent  pre-  gism,  the  terms  subsisting  in  the  same  manner  as 
supra.) (Vlde  the  previous  ones.  For,  first,  let  them  be  affirm- 
lst  case.  Both  ative,1  and  let  A  be  in  every  C,  but  B  contingent 
with  every  C ;  B  C  then  being  convei  ted  there 
will  be  the  first  figure,  and  the  conclusion  will  be  that  A  is 
contingently  present  with  a  certain  B,  for  when  one  premise 
in  the  first  figure  signifies  the  contingent,  the  conclusion  also 
2nd,Minorsim-  was  contingent.  In  like  manner  if  the  proposition 
major  contin^'   B  C2  be  of  the  simple  inesse,  but  the  proposition 

1  "  Predicative." — Averrris.  2  That  is,  the  minor. 


CHAP.  XXI.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  133 

A  C  be  contingent,  and  if  A  C '  be  negative,  but  ,-ent  and  nega- 
B  C  affirmative,  and  either  of  them  be  pure  ;  in  t,ve- 
both  ways  the  conclusion  will  be  contingent,  since  again  there 
arises  the  first  figure.  Now  it  has  been  shown  that  where 
one  premise  in  that  figure  signifies  the  contingent,  the  con- 
clusion also  will  be  contingent ;  if  however  the  negative 
be  annexed  to  the  minor  premise,  or  both  be  as- 
sumed as  negative,  through  the  propositions  laid  gative'minorar 
down  themselves,  there  will  not  indeed  be  a  syllo-    lrom  twonega- 

,      .  -oi  -ii  i  •        fives,  no  syllo- 

gism, but  by  their  conversion-  there  will  be,  as  in    g\&m  results. 

the  former  cases. 

Nevertheless  if  one  premise  be  universal  and    4.  cases  of 
the  other  particular,  yet  both  affirmative,  or  the    Particulars- 
universal  negative   but  the  particular  affirmative,  there  will 
be  the  same  mode  of  syllogisms  ;  for  all  are  com- 
pleted by  the  first  figure,  so  that  it  is  evident  there 
will  be  a  syllogism  of  the  contingent  and  not  of  the  inesse. 
If  however  the  affirmative  be  universal  and  the  negative  par 
ticular,  the  demonstration  will  be  per  impossibile  ; 
for  let  B  be  with  every  C  and  A  happen  not  to  be 
with  a  certain  C,  it  is  necessary  then  that  A  should  happen  not 
to  be  with  a  certain  B,  since  if  A  is  necessarily  with  every  B, 
but  B  is  assumed  to  be  with  every  C,  A  will  necessarily  be  with 
every  C,  which  was  demonstrated  before,  but  by  hypothesis 
A  happens  not  to  be  with  a  certain  C. 

When  both  premises  are  assumed  indefinite,  or  particular,  there 
will  not  be  a  syllogism,  and  the  demonstration  is  the  „  Exam  ]e .,  . 
same  as  in  universals,3  and  by  the  same  terms.* 

1  Major.     2  i.  e.  the  negative  contingent  being  changed  into  affirmative. 

3  Alexander  Aphrodis.  thinks  we  should  read  ?)  Kai  t-rri  twv  t£  au<po- 
t'(Q(jiv  ivStxoy-ii,'»v,  (instead  of  »)  Kai  ivrdiQ  kci06\ov,)  i.  e.  which  was 
in  syllogisms,  both  the  propositions  of  which  are  contingent.— Taylor, 
Julius  Facius,  and  Zell  approve  of  this  emendation,  but  I  agree  with 
Waitz  in  thinking  it  unnecessary.  Cf.  cap.  20,  and  '21. 

Ex.    .  Something  white  |  J^  no(.  >  an  animal 

It  happens  that  something  white  j  ^      t  >  a  man 

It  is  necessary  that  every  man  should  be  an  animal. 

Something   white  I  ^  not  !■  a  horse 

( is        ) 
It  happens  that  something  white  j  jg  no(     a  man 

It  is  necessary  that  no  man  should  be  a  hon>e. 


134  Aristotle's  org  anon.        book 


Chap.  XXII. —  Of  Syllogisms  with  one  Premise  necessary,  and  the 
other  contingent  in  the  third  Figure. 

If  one  premise  be  necessary,  but  the  other  con- 
univ"rsaisf(iii  tingent,  the  terms  being  affirmative  there  will  be 
the  third  figure,  always  a  syllogism  of  the  contingent;  but  when 
sary,  and  the  one  is  affirmative  but  the  other  negative,  if  the 
other  contin-      affirmative  be  necessary  there  will  be  a  syllogism 

gent  premise.  .  J ,  J       p 

ot  the  contingent  non-inesse ;   if  however  it  be 
negative,  there  will  be  one  both  of  the  contingent  and  of  the 
absolute  non-inesse.     There  will  not  however  be  a  syllogism 
of  the  necessary  non-inesse,  as  neither  in  the  other  figures. 
Let  then,  first,  the  terms  be  affirmative,  and  let  A  be  neces- 
Each  propo-   sarily  with  every  C,  but  B  happen  to  be  with  every 
sition,  affirma-    C  ;  therefore  since  A  is  necessarily  with  every  C, 
but  C  is  contingent  to  a  certain  B,  A  will  also  be 
contingently,  and  not  necessarily,  with  some  certain  B  ;  for  thus 
it  is  concluded  in  the  first  figure.     It  can  be  similarly  proved 
*  Example  (i )   if  B  C  be  assumed  as  necessary,  but  A  C  contin- 
gent.* 
2.  Major  nega-       Again,  let  bne  premise  be  affirmative,  but  the 
tive,  minor        other  negative,  and  let  the  affirmative  be  neces- 
sary ;  let  also  A  happen  to  be  with  no  C,  but  let  B 
necessarily  be  with  every  C  ;  again  there  will  be  the  first  figure  ; l 

It  happens  that  something  white    j  ?s        ]  an  animal 

Something  white  |  j*        J  a  man 

It  is  necessary  that  every  man  should  be  an  animal. 

It  happens  that  some  animal  {  ■'         'a  horse 

(is  not ) 

Something  white  ]  'S        J  a  man 
It  is  necessary  that  no  man  should  be  a  horse. 
Ex.  1.  It  happens  that  every  man  is  It  happens  that  every  man  is 

white  white 

It  is  necessary  that  every  man  It  is  necessary  that  some  ani- 

should  be  an  animal  mal  should  be  a  man 

.  • .    It  happens  that  some  animal     .  •  .  It  happens   that  some  animal 

is  white  is  white. 

1  Taylor  inserts  here  —  "  and  the  conclusion  will  be  contingent,  but  ncJ 
pare" — which  is  omitted  by  Waitz. 


CHAP.  XXII.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  135 

for  the  negative  premise  signifies  the  being  contingent  it  is 
evident  therefore  that  the  conclusion  will  be  contingent,  for 
when  the  premises  were  thus  in  the  first  figure,  the  conclusion 
was  also  contingent.  But  if  the  negative  premise  be  neces- 
sary, the  conclusion  will  be  that  it  is  contingent,  not  to  be  with 
something,  and  that  it  is  not  with  it ;  for  let  A  be  supposed 
necessarily  not  with  C,  but  contingent  to  every  B,  then  the 
affirmative  proposition  B  C  being  converted,  there  will  be  the 
first  figure,  and  the  negative  premise  will  be  necessary.  But 
when  the  premises  are  thus,  it  results  that  A  happens  not  to 
be  with  a  certain  C,  and  that  it  is  not  with  it ;  wherefore  it  is  ne- 
cessary also  that  A  should  not  be  with  a  certain  B.    „  _ 

,,,.•'.  ,  .  .        .  .3.  Vice  versa. 

When  however  the  minor  premise  is  assumed  ne- 
gative there  will  be  a  syllogism,  if  that  be  contingent  by  the 
premise  being  converted  as  in  the  former  cases,  but  if  it  be  ne- 
cessary there  will  not  be,  for  it  is  necessary  to  be  with  every,  and 
happens  to  be  with  none  ;  let  the  terms  of  being  with  every  in- 
dividual, be"sleep,"a  "sleeping  horse,"  "man  ;"  of  „ 
being  with  none  "  sleep,"  a  "waking  horse,"  "man."* 
It  will  happen  in  the  same  way,  if  one  term  be 
joined  to  the  middle  universally,  but  the  other   Ucuiars.of  par 
partially,  for  both  being  affirmative  there  will  be 
a  syllogism  of  the  contingent,  and  not  of  the  absolute,  also 
when  the  one  is  assumed  as  negative  but  the  other  affirmative, 
and  the  affirmative  is  necessary.     But  when  the  negative  is 
necessary,  the  conclusion  will  also  be  of  the  not  being  present 
with  ;    for   there   will  be  the  same  mode  of  demonstration, 
whether  the  terms  are  universal  or  not  universal,  since  it  is 
necessary  that  the  syllogisms  be  completed  by  the  first  figure, 
so  that  it  is  requisite  that  the  same  should  result,  in  these,1 

Ex.  2.  It  happens   that    eve*y    man  It  happens  that  every  man  sleeps 
sleeps 

It  is  necessary   that  no  man  It  is  necessary  that  no  man  should 

should  be  a  sleeping  horse         be  a  waking  horse 

It   is    necessary    that   every  It   is    necessary    that  no    waking 
sleeping  horse  should  sleep.         horse  should  sleep. 

Ex.  3.  It   happens   that    some   man  It  happens  that  some  man  sleeps 
sleeps 

It  is  necessary  that  no  man  It  is  necessary  that  no  man  should 

should  be  a  sleeping  horse  be  a  waking  horse 

It    is     necessary   that   every  It   is    necessary   that   no    waking 
sleeping  horse  should  sleep.         horse  should  be  asleep. 
i.  e.  in  syllogisms  of  the  first  tigure. 


136  Aristotle's  org  anon.  [book  i. 

as  in  those.1  When  however  the  negative,  universally  as- 
sumed, is  joined  to  the  less  extreme,  if  it  be  contingent,  there 
will  be  a  syllogism  by  conversion,  but  if  it  be  necessary  there 
will  not  be,  and  this  may  be  shown  in  the  same  mode  as  in 
universals,  and  by  the  same  terms.f  Wherefore 
v  '  in  this  figure  it  it  is  evident,  when  and  how  there 
will  be  a  syllogism,2  and  when  of  the  contingent,  and  when  of 
the  absolute,  all  also  it  is  clear  are  imperfect,  and  are  perfected 
by  the  first  figure. 

Chap.  XXIII. — It  is  demonstrated  that  every  Syllogism  is  completed 

by  the  first  Figure. 

That  the  syllogisms  then  in  these  figures  are  com- 
prdi'minlry'to8  pleted  by  the  universal  syllogisms  in  the  first 
proving  that  figure,  and  are  reduced  to  these,  is  evident  from 
resuHsyfromSm  what  has  been  said  ;  but  that  in  short  every  syllo- 
lVlivsers.aIs  of      gism  is  thus,  will  now  be  evident,  when  it  shall  be 

the  first  figure.    «=  »  ,  »■%■%* 

shown  that  every  syllogism  is  produced  by  some 
one  of  these  figures. 

It  is  then  necessary  that  every  demonstration, 
must  demon-  and  every  syllogism,  should  show  either  something 
lute'unive^s-0  inesse  or  non-inesse,  and  this  either  universally 
ally  or  particu-  or  partially,  moreover  either  ostensively  or  by 
tensive.  e  °%~  hypothesis.  A  part  however  of  that  which  is  by 
hypothesis  is  produced  per  impossible,  therefore 
let  us  first  speak  of  the  ostensive  (syllogisms),  and  when  these 
are  shown,  it  will  be  evident  also  in  the  case  of  those  lead- 
ing to  the  impossibile,  and  generally  of  those  by  hypothesis. 
3.  For  a  sim-  If  then  it  is  necessary  to  syllogize  A  of  B  either 

we  must^av11  as  Dem&  with  or  as  not  being  with,  we  must  as- 
twoproposi-  sume  something  of  something,  if  then  A  be  as- 
sumed of  B,  that  which  was  from  the  first  (pro- 
posed) will  be  assumed  (to  be  proved),  but  if  A  be  assumed 
of  C,  but  C  of  nothing,  nor  any  thing  else  of  it,  nor  of  A,  there 
will  be  no  syllogism,  for  there  is  no  necessary  result  from  as- 
suming one  thing  of  one,  so  that  we  must  take  another  pre- 
mise.    If  then  A  be  assumed  of  something  else,  or  something 

1  In  syllogisms  of  the  third. 

2  i.  e.  there  will  be  a  syllogism  from  hoth  propositions  being  contin- 
gent, or  from  one  being  pure  and  the  other  contingent,  or  from  one  neces- 
sary and  the  other  contingent. 


CHAP.  XXIII. J  THE   PRIOR  ANALYTICS.  137 

else  of  A,  or  of  C,  there  is  nothing  to  hinder  a  syllogism,  it 
will  not  however  appertain  to  B  '  from  the  assumptions.  Nor 
when  C  is  predicated  of  something  else,  and  that  of  another, 
and  this  last  of  a  third,2  if  none  of  these  belong  to  B,  neither 
thus  will  there  be  a  syllogism  with  reference  to  B,  since  in 
short  we  say  that  there  never  will  be  a  syllogism  of  one  thing 
in  respect  of  another  unless  a  certain  middle  is  assumed,  which 
refers  in  some  way  to  each  extreme  in  predication.  For  a 
syllogism  is  simply  from  premises,  but  that  which  pertains  to 
this  in  relation  to  that,  is  from  premises  belonging  to  this  in 
relation  to  that,3  but  it  is  impossible  to  assume  a  premise  re- 
lating to  B,  if  we  neither  affirm  nor  deny  any  thing  of  it,  or 
again  of  A  in  relation  to  B,  if  we  assume  nothing  common, 
but  affirm  or  deny  certain  peculiarities  of  each. 
Hence  a  certain  middle  of  both  must  be  taken,  nectedTy™"" 
which  unites  the  predications,  if  there  shall  be  a  ml^le  term  : 

.r  ,  .p    which  con- 

syllogism  of  one  in  relation  to  the  other ;  now  it  nexion  is  three- 
it  is  necessary  to  assume  something  common  to  A^rici^"16 
both,  this  happens  in  a  three-fold  manner,  (since 
we  either  predicate  A  of  C,  and  C  of  B,4  or  C5  of  both  or 
both  of  C, 6)  but  these  are  the  before-mentioned  figures — it  is 
evident  that  every  syllogism  is  necessarily  produced  by  some 
one  of  these  figures,  for  there  is  the  same  reasoning,  if  A  be 
connected  with  B,  even  through  many  media,  for  the  figure  in 
many  media  will  be  the  same. 

Wherefore   that    all   ostensive  syllogisms    are    2.  of  syiio- 
perfected  by  the  above-named  figures  is  clear,  also   ^s™bl^rt^re 
that  those  per  impossibile  (are  so  perfected)  will   is  the  same 
appear  from  these,  for  all  syllogisms  concluding   method- 
per  impossibile  collect  the  false,  but  they  prove  by  hypothesis 
the  original  proposition,  when  contradiction  being   admitted 
some  impossibility  results,7  as  for  instance  that  the  diameter  of 
a  square  is  incommensurate  with  the  side,  because,  a  common 
measure  being  given,  the  odd  would  be  equal  to  the  even. 

1  A  will  r.ot  be  concluded  of  B— but  something  else. 

2  i.  e.  C  of  D,  D  of  E,  E  of  F. 

3  i.  e.  in  which  the  middle  is  connected  with  each  extreme. 

4  The  first  figure.         5  The  second  figure.         6  The  third  figure. 

7  This,  as  Dr.  Hessey  remarks,  in  his  valuable  tables  upon  the  nature  of 
Enthyinem,  corresponds  very  closely  to  the  definition  of  IXtyKriicbv  iv6v- 
HT)fia  in  the  Rhetoric  ii.  2,  15,  and  to  the  instance  given  Rhetoric  ii.  '24, 
'6.  He  thus  exhibits  the  operation,  which  the  reader  will  find  applied  to 
the  instance  in  the  text,  in  table  4  of  Schemata  Rhetonca. 


138  Aristotle's  org  axon.  [book  i. 

They  collect  then  that,  the  odd  would  be  equal  to  the  even, 
but  show  from  hypothesis  that  the  diameter  is  incommen- 
surate, since  a  falsity  occurs  by  contradiction.  This  then  it 
1.  what  this  J8'  t0  syllogize  per  impossibile,  namely,  to  show  an 
kind  ofsyiio-      impossibility  from  the  original  hypothesis,  so  that 

as  by  reasonings  leading  to  the  impossible,  an 
ostensive  syllogism  of  the  false  arises,  but  the  original  propo- 
sition is  proved  by  hypothesis  ;  and  we  have  before  said 
about  ostensive  syllogisms,  that  they  are  perfected  by  these 
figures — it  is  evident  that  syllogisms  also  per  impossibile  will 
be  formed  through  these  figures.  Likewise  all  others  which 
are  by  hypothesis,  for  in  all  there  is  a  syllogism  of  that  which 
is  assumed,1  but  the  original  proposition  is  proved  by  con- 
fession, or  some  other  hypothesis.  Now  if  this  is  true,  it  is 
necessary  that  every  demonstration  and  syllogism  should  arise 
3.  Also  of  syiio-  t,ir°ugh  the  three  figures  before  named,  and  this 
gisms,  k(  Wo-  being  shown,  it  is  manifest  that  every  syllogism 
capftu'iltion.       is  completed  in  the  first  figure,  and  is  reduced  to 

universal  syllogisms  in  it. 

Chap.  XXIV. — Of  the  Quality  and  Quantity  of  the  Premises  in 
Sy  Hoy  ism. —  Of  the  Conclusion^ 

i.  Oneaffirma-  Moreover  it  is  necessary  in  every  syllogism,  that 
tive  and  one       one  term  should  be  affirmative  and  one  universal. 

universal  term     v.  .,,  .,  .  ,    .  .,,  ' 

necessary.in  all   for  without  the  universal  there  will  not  be  a  syllo- 

syll0(Prooi.')       Sism>  or  one  not  pertaining  to  the  thing  proposed, 

or  the  original  (question)  will  be  the  subject  of 

petition.2     For  let  it  be  proposed  that  pleasure  from  music  is 

If  A  is  B,  then  P  is  Q, 
But  that  P  is  Q  is  absurd. 

.  • .  If  it  is  absurd  to  say  that  P  is  Q,  it  is  absurd  to  say  that  A  is  B. 
.  •  .  A  is  not  B.    Q.  E.  D. 

1  Trpbq,  to  HETakanfiavofttvov. — For  example,  in  the  hypothetical 
syllogism— If  the  soul  is  moved  by  itself  it  is  immortal:  but  it  is  moved 
by  itself,  .  •  .  it  is  immortal :  the  assumption  is,  the  soul  is  moved  by 
itself.  The  disjunctive  syllogism  owes  its  origin  to  the  airaywyij  iirjTo 
advvarov,  one  of  the  principal  kinds  of  hypotheticals  mentioned  by  Aris- 
totle, whose  use  of  the  latter  expression,  it  is  necessary  to  remember,  is 
not  opposed  to  categorical,  but  to  ostensive  (Suktikoq)  syllogism,  as  in 
this  very  chapter.  The  reader  is  referred  for  some  valuable  observations 
upon  this  subject  to  note  G,  Appendix,  Mansel's  Logic.  Hypothetical 
syllogisms,  as  we  employ  the  term,  are  not  discussed  by  Aristotle  ;  vide 
Aldrich  de  Syiloeismis  Hypotheticis. 

'  airijatrai.    Distinction  is  not   an   Aristotelian   term,  but  the    rules 


CHAP.  XXIV.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  139 

commendable,  if  then  any  one  should  require  it  to  be  granted 
that  pleasure  is  commendable,  and  did  not  add  all  pleasure, 
there  would  not  be  a  syllogism,  but  if  that  a  certain  pleasure 
is  so,  if  indeed  it  is  a  different  pleasure,  it  is  nothing  to  the 
purpose,  but  if  it  is  the  same  it  is  a  petitio  principii,  this  will 
however  be  more  evident  in  diagrams,  for  instance,  let  it  be 
required  to  show  that  the  angles  at  the  base  of  an  isosceles 
triangle  are  equal.1  Let  the  lines  A  B  be  drawn  to  the  centre  of 
a  circle,  if  then  he  assumes  the  angle  A  C  to  be  equal  to  the 
angle  B  D,  not  in  short  requiring  it  to  be  granted  that  the  angles 
of  semicircles  are  equal,  and  again  that  C  is  equal  to  D,  not 
assuming  the  whole  (angle)  of  the  section,  if  besides  he  assumes 
that  equal  parts  being  taken  from  equal  whole  angles,  the  re- 
maining angles  E  F  are  equal,  he  will  beg  the  original  (question), 
unless  he  assume  that  if  equals  are  taken  from  equals  the  remain- 
ders are  equal.  Wherefore  in  all  syllogism  we  must  have  an 
universal ;  universal  is  also  shown  from  all  universal  terms,  but 
the  particular  in  this  or  that  way,  so  that  if  the 
conclusion  be  universal,  the  terms  must  of  necessity  c^uston*"?- 
be  universal,  but  if  the  terms  be  universal,  the    lows  froni  uni- 

i       ■  ,  i_  ■  i      • -r       versal  premises 

conclusion  may  happen  not  to  be  universal.     It  but  sometimes 

appears  also  that  in  every  syllogism  either  both  j^iy  a  particu- 

premises  or  one  of  them  must  be  similar  to  the  3.  One  premise 

conclusion.  I  mean  not  only  in  its  being  affirm-  SStaSSta 

ative  or  negative,but  in  that  it  is  either  necessarv,  in  character 

,       i     ,  ,.  ,         ,      •"     and  quality. 

or  absolute,  or  contingent  ;   we  must  also  have 
regard  to  other  modes  of  predication.2 

In  a  word  then  it  is  shown  when  there  will  and  will  not  be  a 
syllogism,  also  when  it  is  possible,3  and  when  per- 
fect, and  that  when  there  is  a  syllogism  it  must  have   t"  RecaPitula- 

*        °  tion. 

its  terms  according  to  some  one  of  the  above  modes. 


belonging  thereto  are  implied  in  his  account  of  the  figures.  The  several 
directions  given  by  Aldrich,  on  the  construction  of  syllogistic  inquiry, 
occur  successively  in  this  and  the  succeeding  chapters,  as  comprised  in 
the  old  memorial — "  Distribuas  Medium,"  etc. 

1  This  is  demonstrated  in  one  way  by  Euclid,  and  in  another  by  Pap- 
pus. See  also  Proclus  Commen.  lib.  i.  Euclid.  Elem.  One  of  the  five 
modes  of  the  "petitio  principii,"  is  not  in  form  distinguishable  from  the 
legitimate  syllogism.    Conf.  Top.  viii.  13;    Anal.  Pr.  ii.  16. 

2  As  the  impossible,  probable,  etc. 

3  By  possible  here  he  means  an  imperfect,  which  may  be  brought  into 
fc  perfect  syllogism.     For  the  elucidation  of  tins  chapter  and  the  follow- 


140  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  l 

Chap.  XXV. — Every  Syllogism  cotisists  of  only  three  Terms,  and 

of  two  Premises. 

1.  Demor.stra-  It  appears  that  every  demonstration  Avill  be  by 
tion is  ™™ev~  three  terms  and  no  more,  unless  the  same  con- 
terms  only—  elusion  should  result  through  different '  arguments, 
proof-  as  E2  through  A  B,3  and  through  C  D,4  or  through 

A  B,  A  C,  and  B  C,  for  there  is  nothing  to  prevent  many 
media  subsisting  of  the  same  (conclusions).  But  these  being 
(many),  there  is  not  one  syllogism,  but  many  syllogisms  ;  or 
again,  when  each  of  the  propositions  A  B  is  assumed  by  syl- 
logism, as  A  through  D  E,5  and  again  B  through 

g  thehmSor°r'  F  &,*  or  when  the  one  is  hY  induction,6  but  the 
other  by  syllogism.  Thus  in  this  manner  indeed 
there  are  many  syllogisms,  for  there  are  many  conclusions,  as 
A  and  B  and  C,  and  if  there  are  not  many  but  one,  it  is  thus 
possible,  that  the  same  conclusion  may  arise 
conciusfoTmay  thruugh  many  syllogisms,  but  in  order  that  C  may 
maneyfsyno-  be  Proved  through  A  B,  it  is  impossible.!  For 
gisms.  let  the  conclusion  be  E,  collected  from  ABCD, 

there6  should  be  it  is  then  necessary  that  some  one  of  these  should 
more  than  foe  assumed  with  reference  to  something  else,  as  a 
whole,  but  another  as  a  part,  for  this  has  been 
shown  before,  that  when  there  is  a  syllogism,  some  of  the 
terms  should  necessarily  thus  subsist ;  let  then  A  be  thus  with 
reference  to  B,  from  these  there  is  a  certain  conclusion,  which 
is  either  E  or  C  or  D,  or  some  other  different  from  these. 

ing  more  particularly,  the  reader  is  referred  to  Mansel's,  Whalely's,  and 
Hill's  Logic. 

1  The  Leipsic  copy  omits  the  example,  and  Taylor's  reading  is  some- 
what different  to  that  of  Averrois,  Buhle,  and  Waitz.  By  demon- 
stration Aristotle  here  means  syllogism  generally. 

2  The  conclusion.  3  A  the  major,  B  the  minor. 

4  C  the  major,  D  the  minor. 

5  A  the  major  of  the  prosyllogism  in  which  the  major  of  the  principal 
syllogism  is  proved — E  the  minor  of  the  same.  Though  in  the  first  part 
E  signifies  the  conclusion  of  the  principal  syllogism,  yet  the  conclusion  is 
at  present  called  C. — Taylor. 

6  As  far  as  induction  is  logical  at  all,  in  its  process  it  is  equally  formal 
with,  though  it  proceeds  in  an  inverse  order  to,  syllogism.  It  is  defined 
by  Aristotle,  proving  the  major  term  of  the  middle  by  means  of  the  minor. 
Anal.  Pr.  ii.  23,  The  Sorites  is  not  recognised  distinctively  by  Aristotle, 
though,  as  Melancthon  observes,  it  is  implied  in  Cat.  3,  and  is  alluded  to 
in  this  chapter ;  its  distinct  exposition  is  attributed  to  the  Stoics. 


CHAP.  XXV.]  THE    TRIOR   ANALYTICS.  14 

Now  if  E  is  concluded,  the  syllogism  would  be  from  A  B 
alone,  but  it'  C  D  are  so  as  that  the  one  is  universal,  and  the 
other  particular,  something  also  will  result  from  these  which 
will  either  be  E  or  A  or  B,  or  something  else  different  from 
these,  and  if  E  is  collected,  or  A  or  B,  there  will  be 
either  many  syllogisms,  or,  as  it  was  shown  possible,  the  same 
thing  will  happen  to  be  collected  through  many  terms.  If, 
however,  any  thing  else  different  from  these  is  collected,  there 
will  be  many  syllogisms  unconnected  with  each  other ;  but  if 
C  is  not  so  with  respect  to  D,  as  to  produce  a  syllogism,  they 
will  be  assumed  to  no  purpose,  except  for  the  sake  of  induction 
or  concealment,  or  something  of  the  sort.  Still  if  from  A  B, 
not  E,  but  some  other  conclusion  is  produced,  and  from  C  D, 
either  one  of  these,  or  something  different  from  these,  many 
syllogisms  arise,  yet  not  of  the  subject,  for  it  was  supposed 
that  the  syllogism  is  of  E.  If,  again,  there  is  no  conclusion 
from  C  D,  it  will  happen  that  they  are  assumed  in  vain,  and 
the  syllogism  is  not  of  the  primary  problem,  so  that  it  is  evi- 
dent that  every  demonstration  and  every  syllogism  will  be 
through  three  terms  only.1 

This  then  being  apparent,  it  is  ako  clear  that    3  These  threg 
a  syllogism  consists  of  two  premises  and  no  more  j  terms  are  in- 
for  three  terms  are  two  premises,  unless  some-   propositTonI° 
thing  is  assumed  over  and  above,  as  we  observed   Vi<je  <vldri^h 
at    first,    for    the    perfection    of  the    syllogisms. 
Hence  it  appears,  that  in  the  syllogistic  discourse,  in  which 
the  premises,  through  which  the  principal  conclusion  is  col- 
lected, are  not  even, — (for  it  is  requisite  that  some  of  the 
former   conclusions   should   be  premises,) — this   discourse   is 
either  not  syllogistically  constructed,2  or  has  required  more 
than  is  necessary  to  the  thesis. 

When  then  the  syllogisms  are  taken  according  to  the  prin- 
cipal propositions,  every  syllogism  will  consist  of  propositions 

1  The  prosyllogism,  or  antecedent  syllogism  of  Aristotle,  is  a  syllogism 
used  to  prove  one  of  the  premises  of  another  syllogism.  Vide  Pucitis 
Anal.  Pr.  i.  35.    Biese,  vol.  i.  p.  157. 

2  Taylor  erroneously  uses  the  active  here,  contrary  to  Waitz  and 
Averrois,  the  latter  translates  (avXXtXoyicrai)  similarly  to  the  rendering 
above — "est  nUiocinatu."  Aristotle  calls  a  thesis,  the  consequent  "ex- 
tra syllogismum  spectata,"  as  Aldricfa  says,  that  is,  the  "problem," 
"question,"  to  '^tov^ivov — the  last,  however,  is  used  mere  extensively 
in  signification.    Vid.  An.  Post,  i.  1,  and  ii.  3. 


142  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

which  are  even,  but  of  terms  which  are  odd  for  the  terms 
exceed  the  premises  by  one,  and  the  conclusic  ns  will  be  half 
part  of  the  premises.1  When,  however,  the  conclusion  results 
through  pro-syllogisms,  or  through  many  continued  middles,2 
as  A  B  through  C  I),  the  multitude  of  terms,  in 
.Vt— incidens  like  manner,  will  exceed  the  premises  by  one,  (tor 
BuhieUS  tne  *erm  interpolated  will  be  added  either  exter- 

nally or  in  the  middle ;  but  in  both  ways  it  will 
happen  that  the  intervals  are  fewer  than  the  terms  by  one,) 
but  the  propositions  are  equal  to  the  intervals,  the  former, 
indeed,  will  not  always  be  even,  but  the  latter  odd,  but  alter- 
nately, when  the  propositions  are  even  the  terms  are  odd,  but 
when  the  terms  are  even  the  propositions  are  odd ;  for  toge- 
ther with  the  term,  one  proposition  is  added  wherever  the 
term  is  added.3     Hence,  since  the   propositions 

4.  Ofthenum-  tii  i  i    -.l  •  ,1 

ber  of  terms,  were  even,  but  the  terms  odd,  it  is  necessary  they 
propositions,       should  change  when  the  same  addition  is  made ; 

and  conclu-  ,  _  °  -n  i 

sions  in  com-  but  the  conclusions  will  no  longer  have  the  same 
£'isSms.sy1*0  order,  neither  with  respect  to  the  terms,  nor  to 
the  propositions,  for  one  term  being  added,  con- 
clusions will  be  added  less  than  the  pre-existent  terms  by  one, 
.  „,,      .  because  to  the  last  term  alone*  there  is  no  con- 

*   1  he  minor. 

elusion  made ;  but  to  all  the  rest,  e.  g.  if  D  is 
added  to  ABC,  two  conclusions  are  immediately  added,  the 
one  to  A  and  the  other  to  B.  The  same  occurs  in  the  other 
cases  also,  if  the  term  be  inserted  in  the  middle  after  the  same 
manner,  for  it  will  not  make  a  syllogism  to  one  term  alone,  so 
that  the  conclusions  will  be  many  more  than  the  terms,  and 
than  the  propositions. 

Chap.  XXVI. — On  the  comparative  Difficulty  of  certain  Problems, 
and  by  what  Figures  they  are  proved} 

i.  The  conciu-  Since  we  have  those  particulars  with  which  syl- 
figures  consti-  logisms  are  conversant,  and  what  is  their  quality 
stutes  the  leia-   in  each  figure,  and  in  how  many  ways  demon- 

1   For  there  is  one  conclusion  to  two  propositions. 
*  As  in  Sorites.     Vide  Mansel's  Logic,  p.  83. 

3  At  the  beginning,  middle,  or  end.    See  Waitz,  vol.  i.  p.  440,  and  441. 

4  Edocemur  hoc  capite  et  seq.,  quomodo  ars  dialectica  cohaereat  cuia 
demunstrandi  arte,  Topiea  cum  Analyticis.     Waitz. 


CHAP.  XXVI.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  143 

stration   takes  place,  it  is   also    manifest  to   us,   tire  facility  of 

■     i      <•  »  i  •      ■!•«»  ii  demonstration. 

what  kind  of  problem  is  difficult,  ana  what  easy   Enumeration 
of  proof,   for  that  which  is  concluded  in  many   £on^t°£cl£ 
figures,  and  through  many  cases,  is  more  easy,  but    cond  figures,. 
what  is  in  fewer  figures,  and  by  fewer  cases,  is  more  difficult. 
An  universal  affirmative  then  is  proved  through  the  first  figure 
alone,   and  by  this  in  one  way  only ;  but  a  negative,  both 
through  the  first  and  through  the  middle,  tnrough  the  first  in 
one  way,  but  through  the  middle  in  two  ways  ;  the  particular 
affirmative  again  through  the  first  and  through  the  last,  in  one 
way  through  the  first  figure,  but  in  three  ways  through  the 
last  ;  lastly,  the  particular  negative  is  proved  in  all  the  figures, 
but  in  the  first  in  one  way,  in  the  middle  in  two  ways,  and  in 
the  last  in  three  ways.     Hence  it  appears  most 
difficult  to  construct  an  universal  affirmative,  but  easierof  sub- 
most  easy  to  subvert  it,  in  short,  universals  are   ^ticuiars4" 
easier  to   subvert  than   particulars,  because  the 
former  are  subverted,  whether  a  thing  is  present  with  nothing, 
or  is  not  with  a  certain  thing,  of  which  the  one,  namely,  the  not 
being  with  a  certain  thing,  is  proved  in  all  the  figures,  and  the 
other,  the  being  with  nothing,  is  proved  in  two.  The  same  mode 
also  prevails  in  the  case  of  negatives,  for  the  original  proposition 
is  subverted,  whether  a  thing  is  with  every,  or  with  a  certain 
individual,1  now  thiswas  in  two  figures.  In  particular  problems 
there  is  one  way  (of  confutation),  either  by  showing  a  thing 
to  be  with  every,  or  with  no  individual,  and  parti-    3  Partjcuiars 
cular  problems  are  easier  of  construction,  for  they   easier  of  con- 
are  in  more  figures,  and  through  more  modes.2    In 
3hort,  we   ought  not  to  forget  that  it  is  possible  to  confute 
universal  mutually   through  particular  problems,   and  these 
through  universal,  yet  we  cannot  construct  universal  through 
particular,  but  the  latter  may  be  through  the  former,  at  the 
same  time  that  it  is  easier  to  subvert  than  to  construct  is  plain. 
In  what  manner  then  every  syllogism  arises,  through  how 

1  This  clause  is  omitted  by  Taylor. 

2  Aristotle  employs  7rrioaig  here  in  the  sense  of  rpoirog,  which  latter  is 
not  an  Aristotelian  expression,  except,  as  some  think,  in  cap.  28  of  this 
book.  He  shows  in  each  figure  what  prepositional  combinations  are 
admissible.  In  Apuleius  there  is  a  distinction  between  modi,  or  moduli, 
and  conjugationes,  the  former  referring  to  combinations  of  three  propc 
sitions,  the  latter  to  ihose  of  two. 


•44  akistotle's  organon.  [book  I. 

many  terms  and  premises,  how  they  subsist  with 
tion.eCaP'tula     reference  to  each  other,  also  what  sort  of  problem 

may  be  proved  in  each  figure,  and  what  in  many 
and  in  fewer  modes,  may  be  gathered  from  what  has  been  said.1 

CHAP.  XXVII.  —  Of  the  Invention  and  Construction  of  Syllogisms? 

1.  How  to  pro-  We  must  now  describe  how  we  may  always  obtain 
gismsylfrom  a  provision  of  syllogisms  for  a  proposed  question, 
certain  princi-  and  in  what  way  we  may  assume  principles  about 
p  es'  each,  for  perhaps  it  is  not  only  requisite  to  con- 
sider the  production  of  syllogisms,  but  also  to  possess  the 
power  of  forming  them. 

2.  The  several  Of  all  beings  then,  some  are  of  such  a  nature 
sons  of  predi-     as  not  to  be  truly  predicated  universally  of  any 

cfltc  s      Soni6 

cannot  be  truly  thing  else,  as  "Cleon,"  and  "Callias,"  that  which 

versanyteofUni"  *s  singular>3  and  that  which  is  sensible,  but  others 

other  than  in-  are  predicated  of  these,  (for  each  of  these  is  man 

ivi  ua  s,  etc.  ancj  annlia])  .   some  again  are  predicated  of  others, 

but  others  not  previously  of  these  ;  lastly,  there  are  some 
which  are  themselves  predicated  of  others,  and  others  of  them, 
as  "man  "  is  predicated  of  Callias,  and  "  animal "  of  man.  That 
some  things  therefore  are  naturally  adapted  to  be  predicated  of 
nothing  is  clear,  for  of  sensibles  each  is  almost  of  such  a  sort,  as 
not  to  be  predicated  of  any  thing  except  accidentally,  for  we 
sometimes  say  that  that  white  thing  is  Socrates,  and  that  the 
object  approaching  is  Callias.  But  that  we  must  stop  some- 
videb.  i.ch.  19,  where  in  our  upward  progression  we  will  again 
Post  Anal.,  et '  show,  for  the  present  let  this  be  admitted.  Of  these 
things  then  we  cannot  point  out  another  predicate, 

1  As  a  digest  of  the  method  of  proof,  we  may  state  that 

A  is  proved  in  one  figure  and  one  mood 

E     —    —      two  figures  and  three  moods 

I      —     —       two     —     —       four 

O     —     —       three  —     —       six. 
Thus  A  is  the  easiest  to  overthrow,  and  the  nearest  to  establish :  0  the 
reverse. 

2  Averrois,  following  the  old  divisions,  commences  his  2nd  section  here 
"  De  abundantia  Propositionum." 

3  The  employment  of  singulars  as  predicates,  is  open  to  much  objection, 
in  connexion  with  singular  propositions.  See  the  Thesis  appended  to 
Wallis's  Logic. 


CBAP.  XXVII.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  145 

except  according  to  opinion,  but  these  may  be  predicated  of 
others,  nor  can  singulars '  be  predicated  of  others,  but  others 
of  them.     It  appears  however  that  those  which  are  interme- 
diate, are  capable  in  both  ways  (of  demonstration),  for  they 
may  be  predicated  of  others,  and  others  of  them,  and  argu- 
ments and  speculations  are  almost  all  conversant  with  these. 
Still  it  is  requisite  to  assume  the  propositions   2.  How  to  as- 
about  each  thing  thus : — In  the   first  place,  the   sP™e  Pr°P°- 
subject,  (by  hypothesis,)  the  definitions,  and  such   these,SinSorder 
peculiarities  as  exist  of  the  thing  ;  next,  whatever   t0  inferenee- 
things  are  consequent  to  the  thing,  and  which  the  thing  fol- 
lows ;2  lastly,  such  as  cannot  be  in  it ;  those  however  which  it 
cannot  be  in  are  not  to  be  assumed,  because  of  the  conversion 
of  the  negative.     We  must  also  distinguish  in  the  consequents 
what  things  belong  to  "what  a  thing  is,"  what  are  predicated 
as  properties,3  and  what  as  accidents  ;  also  of  these,  those  which 
are  (predicated)  according  to  opinion,  and  those,  according  to 
truth  ;    for  the  greater  number  any  one  has  of 
these,  the  quicker  will  he  light  upon  a  conclusion,    h  Distinction. 
and  the  more  true  they  are,  the  more  will  he  de- 
monstrate.    We  must  too  select  not  those  which  are  conse- 
quent to  a  certain  one,  but  those  which  follow  the  whole  thing, 
e.  g.  not  what  follows  a  certain  man,  but  what  follows  every 
man,  for  a  syllogism  consists  of  universal  propositions.     If 
therefore  a  proposition  is  indefinite,  it  is  doubtful  whether  it  is 
universal,  but  when  it  is  definite,  this  is  manifest.     So  also  we 
must  select  those  things  the  whole  of  which  a  thing  follows, 
for  the  reason  given  above,  but  the  whole  consequent  itself 
need  not  be  assumed  to  follow  ;  I  say  for  instance,  (it  must  not 
be  assumed)  that  every  "  animal  "  is  consequent  to  "  man,"  or 
every  science  to  music,  but  only  that  they  are  simply  conse- 
quent, as  we  set  forth,4  for  the  other  is  useless  and  impossible,5 
as  that  "every  man"  is  "every  animal,"  or  that  "justice  is 
every  thing  good."     To  whatever  (subject)  a  consequent  is 
attached,  the  sign  "every"  is  added  ;  when  however  the  sub- 

1  Taylor   here   falls    into    his    common    mistake    of  translating    kci8' 
Uacra — "  particular."     Averrois,  '«  singularia  " — which  is  right. 

2  Omitted  by  Taylor. 

3  The  idiov,  both  by  Porphyry  and  Aristotle,  is  considered  as  co-exten- 
sive and  convertible  with  its  subject,  and  answers  to  the  fourth  predicable. 

1   i.  e.  as  we  form  propositions. 
That  is,  a  predicate  with  the  universal  sign. 


146  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

ject  is  comprehended  by  a  certain  thing,1  the  consequents 
of  which  we  must  assume,  those  which  follow  or  which  do 
not  follow  the  universal,  we  are  not  to  select  in  these — for 
they  were  assumed  in  those,  since  whatever  are  consequent  to 
"  animal,"  are  also  consequent  to  "  man,"  and  as  to  whatever 

things  are  not  absolutely  present  with  in  like  man- 
sumed.  °vlde  ner ;  but  the  properties  of  each  thing  must  be 
Aidrich  and       taken,  for  there  are  certain  properties  in  species 

not  common  to  genus,  since  it  is  necessary  that 
certain  properties  should  be  in  different  species.  Nor  are  we 
to  select  those  in  regard  to  the  universal,  which  the  thing  com- 
prehended follows,  as  those  which  "  man  "  follows  ought  not 
to  be  assumed  to  "  animal,"  for  it  is  necessary  if  animal  fol- 
lows man  that  it  follows  all  these,2  but  these  more  properly 
belong  to  the  selection  of  the  antecedents  of  "  man."  3  We  must 
also  assume  those  which  are  generally  consequent  and  antece- 
dent, for  of  general  problems  the  syllogism  also  is  from  propo- 
sitions, all  or  some  of  which  are  general,  as  the  conclusion  of 
each  syllogism  resembles  its  principles.  Lastly,  we  are  not  to 
select  things  consequent  to  all,  since  there  will  not  be  composed 
a  syllogism  from  them,  on  account  of  a  reason  which  will  ap- 
pear from  what  follows. 

Chap.  XXVIII. — Special  Rules  upon  the  same  Subject. 
,  „^  .  t    ,j    Those  therefore  who  desire  to  confirm  any  thing 

1.  What  should  .  .  iii-iii  i  •>  • 

betheinspec-  of  a  certain  universal,  should  look  to  the  subject 

that  Munf  matter  of  what  is  confirmed,  in  respect  of  which 

versai  or  parti-  it  happens  to  be  predicated  ;  but  of  whatever  ought 

ative  or  nega-  to  be  predicated,  of  this,  he  should  examine  the 

tive  may  be  de-  consequents  :  for  if  one  of  these  happens  to  be  the 

monstrated.  i  »  ...        j  r  ._ 

same,  one  must  necessarily  be  in  the  other.     But 
if  (it  is  to  be  proved)  that  a  thing  is  not  present  universally 
but  particularly,  he  must  examine  those  which  each  follows,4 
for  if  any  of  these  is  the  same,  to  be  particularly  present  is 

1  i.  e.  by  an  universal  predicate. 

2  Of  which  man  is  predicated. 

*  That  is,  the  subjects  to  man  ought  to  be  chosen  and  assumed  per 
»e.  The  reader  is  referred  for  the  rules  specified  here  to  the  commoi 
Logics,  especially  Whately,  b.  ii.  c.  111. 

*  The  antecedent  of  both  predicate  and  subject. 


CHAP.  XXVIII. J  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  147 

necessary  ;  but  when  the  presence  with  nothing  is  necessary,1 
as  to  what  it  need  not  be  present  with,2  we  must  look  to  those 
which  cannot  be  present  with  it  ;3  or  on  the  contrary,  (as  regards 
that)  with  which4  it  is  necessary  not  to  be  present,  we  must 
look  to  those  which  cannot  be  with  it,  but  as  to  what  ought 
not  to  be  present,  to  the  consequents.  For  whichever  of  these 
are  identical,  it  will  happen  that  the  one  is  in  no  other,  since 
sometimes  a  syllogism  arises  in  the  first  and  at  other  times  in 
the  middle  figure.  If  however  the  particular  non-inesse  (is 
to  be  proved),  that  with  which  it  ought  not  to  be  present,  and 
those  which  it  follows,  are  to  be  looked  to ;  but  of  that  which 
ought  not  to  be  present,  those  must  be  considered,  which  it  is 
impossible  can  be  in  it,  for  if  any  of  these  be  identical  the 
particular  non-inesse  is  necessary.  What  has  been  said  how- 
ever will  perhaps  be  more  clear  thus.  Let  the  consequents  to 
A  be  B,  but  let  those  to  which  it  is  consequent  be  C  ;  those 
again  which  cannot  be  in  it,  D  ;  again,  let  the  things  present 
with  E  be  F,  and  those  to  which  it  is  consequent,  G ;  lastly, 
those  which  cannot  be  in  it,  H.  Now  if  a  certain  C  and  a 
certain  F  are  identical,  it  is  necessary  that  A  should  be  with 
every  E,  for  F  is  present  with  every  E,  and  A  with  every  C, 
so  that  A  is  with  every  E ;  but  if  C  and  G  are  identical,  A 
must  necessarily  be  with  a  certain  E,  for  A  follows  every  C,  and 
E  every  G.  If  however  F  and  D  are  identical,  A  will  be  with 
no  E  from  a  pro-syllog:sm,5  for  since  a  negative  is  convertible 
and  F  is  identical  with  D,  A  will  be  with  no  F,  but  F  is  with  every 
E  ;  again,  if  B  and  H  are  the  same,  A  will  be  with  no  E,  for  B 
is  with  every  A,  but  with  no  E,  for  it  was  the  same  as  II, 
and  H  was  with  no  E.  If  D  and  G  are  identical,  A  will  not 
be  with  a  certain  E,  for  A  will  not  be  with  G,  since  it  is  not 
present  with  D,  but  G  is  under  E,  so  that  neither  will  it  be 
with  a  certain  E.  Moreover  if  B  is  identical  with  G  there  will 
be  an  inverse  syllogism,  for  G  will  be  with  every  A,  (since  B  is 
with  A,)  and  E  with  B  (for  B  is  the  same  as  G) ;  still  it  is 
not  necessary  that  A  should  be  with  every  E,  but  it  is  neces- 

1  When  E  was  to  be  proved. 

2  i.  e.  the  subject  of  the  question. 

3  Taylor  inserts  with  Buhle  here  tic  to.  tnofitva,  which  alters  the  sense. 
I  follow  Waitz. 

4  The  predicate.  The  confusion  of  the  various  readings  here  is  endless. 
*  In  which  the  major  premise  of  the  principal  syllogism  is  proved. 


148  Aristotle's  organon.  Tbook 


L- 


sary  that  it  be  with  a  certain  E,  because  an  universal  predi- 
cation may  be  converted  into  a  particular  one. 

Wherefore  we  must  evidently  regard  what  has 
tion  of  the  pro-  been  mentioned  as  to  each  part  of  every  problem,1 
amlned  be  eX  since  all  syllogisms  are  from  these  ;  but  in  conse- 
quents, and  the  antecedents  of  each  thing,  we 
must  look  to  first  elements,  and  to  those  which  are  for  the 
most  part  universal,  as  in  the  case  of  E  we  must  look  more  to 
K  F  than  only  to  F,2  hut  in  the  case  of  A  more  to  K  C  than 
to  C  only.  For  if  A  is  present  with  K  C  it  is  also  present 
with  F  and  with  E,3  but  if  it  is  not  consequent  to  this,  yet  it 
may  be  consequent  to  F ;  in  like  manner  we  must  examine 
those  which  the  thing  itself  is  consequent  to,  for  if  it  follows 
the  primary,  it  also  does  those  which  are  included  under  them, 
and  if  it  does  not  follow  these,  yet  it  may  those  which  are 
arranged  under  them.4 

Speculation  then,  plainly,  consists  of  three  terms  and  two 

propositions,  and  all  syllogisms  are  through  the 

eons-istsof three   above-mentioned  figures  ;  for  A  is  shown  present 

terms  and  two    wjth  every  E,  when  of  C  and  F  something  iden- 

propositions.  r 

tical  may  be  assumed.  Now  this  will  be  the  mid- 
dle term,5  and  A  and  E  the  extremes,  and  there  is  the  first 
figure,  but  (presence  with)  a  certain  thing  is  shown  when  C 
and  G  are  assumed  identical,  and  this  is  the  last  figure,  for  G 
becomes  the  middle.  Again,  (presence  with)  none,  when  D 
and  F  are  identical,  but  thus  also  the  first  figure  and  the 
middle  are  produced  ;  the  first,  because  A  is  with  no  F,  (since 
a  negative  is  converted,)  but  F  is  with  every  E  ;  and  the 
middle  because  D  is  with  no  A,  but  with  every  E.  Not  to 
be  present  also  with  a  certain  one,  (is  shown)  when  D  and  G 
are  the  same,  and  this  is  the  last  figure,  for  A  will  be  with 
no  G,  and  E  with  every  G.  Wherefore  all  syllogisms  are 
evidently  through  the  above-named  figures,  and  we  must  not 
select  those  which  are  consequent  to  all,  because  no  syllogism 
arises  from  them  ;  as,  in  short,  we  cannot  construct  from  con- 

'   As  to  both  subject  and  predicate. 

"  K  F  is  the  genus  of  both  K  and  F,  and  K  C  stands  in  the  same  rela- 
tion to  K  and  C.  3  F  is  contained  under  K,  and  E  under  F. 

4  Thus  if  "living"  follows  "animal,"  it  also  follows"  man,"  and 
though  it  does  not  follow  "body,"  it  follows  that  whichis  under  "  body." 
- — Taylor 

*  viz.  C  F — A  the  major— E  the  minor. 


CHAP.  XXVIII.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  149 

sequents,  nor  deduce  a  negative  through  an  universal  conse- 
quent, for  it  must  be  in  one,  and  not  in  the  other.1 

TLat  other  modes  of  speculation2  also,  as  regards  selection, 
are  useless  for  the  construction  of  syllogism  is  apparent ;  for 
instance,  if  the  consequents  to  each  are  identical,  or  if  those 
which  A  (the  predicate)  follows,  and  which  can-   4.  other  modes 
not  be  with  E  (the  subject),  or  again  those  which   J,,™^6^™ 
cannot  concur  to  be  with  either,  for  no  syllogism   gards  selection 
arises   through  these.     If  then   the  consequents 
are  identical,  as  B  and  F,  the  middle  figure  is  produced,  having 
both  premises  affirmative  ;  but  if  those  which  A  follows,  and 
which  cannot  be  with  E,  as  C  and  H,  there  will  be  the  first 
figure  having  the  minor  premise  negative  ;  again,  if  those  are 
identical  which  cannot  be  with  either,  as  D  and  H,3  both  pro- 
positions will  be  negative,  either  in  the  first  or  in  the  middle 
figure  :  thus,  however,  there  will  by  no  means  be  a  syllogism. 

We  see  moreover  that  we  must  assume  in  spe- 
culation things  identical,  and  not  what  are  different,    seiecte i™ in ves- 

or  contrary ;  first,  because  our  inspection  is  for   ligation,  not 
,  ,  ..     .  .in  i  1  tna'  wherein 

the  sake  01  the  middle,  and  we  must  take  as  a  the  terms  differ, 
middle,  not  what  is  different,  but  what  is  identical.  theyLreeth 
Next,  in  whatever  a  syllogism  happens  to  be  pro- 
duced, from  the  assumption  of  contraries,  or  of  those  things 
which  cannot  be  with  the  same,  all  are  reduced  to  the  before- 
named  modes,  as  if  B  and  F  are  contraries,  or  cannot  be  with 
the  same  thing  ;  if  these  are  assumed  there  will  be  a  syllo- 
gism that  A  is  with  no  E  :  this  however  does  not  result  from 
them,  but  from  the  above-named  mode ;  for  B  is  with  every 
A,  and  with  no  E,  so  that  B  must  necessarily  be  identical 
with  a  certain  H.  Again,  if  B  and  G  do  not  concur  to  be 
with  the  same  thing,  (it  will  follow)  that  A  will  not  be  with 
a  certain  E,  and  so  there  will  be  the  middle  figure,  for  B  is 

1  That  is,  he  who  wishes  to  conclude  a  negative  must  take  a  middle, 
which  concurs  with  one  extreme,  and  not  with  the  other,  but  in  the  case 
cited  both  propositions  would  be  affirmative — here  KaraoKtva^Hv,  "affir- 
mative colligere,"  is  opposed  to  a Troartpuv,  "  negative  colligere."  Confer. 
Waltz,  vol.  i.  page  45U. 

*  artiste  rwv  Kara  rag  tfcXoyag  dxptloi. — Vide  Waitz,  vol.  i.  451,  and 
Biese,  i.  p.  160,  also  Mansel's  Logic,  page  79.  See  also  the  definition  of 
roiroc  given  by  Cicero  (Top.  ch.  ii.)  ;  the  name  originally  alluded  to  the 
plafc  in  which  we  look  for  middle  terms.  Vide  liliei.  ii.  2t>.  1 ;  also  note 
o'i  Top.  i.  I. 

1  Taylor  reads  G,  en  ^neously. 


1,30  Aristotle's  org  anon.  [hook  l 

with  every  A,  and  with  no  G,1  so  that  B  must  necessarily  be 
identical  with  some  H.  For  the  impossibility  of  B  and  G 
being  in  the  same  thing,  does  not  differ  from  B  being  the 
same  as  a  certain  H,  since  every  thing  is  assumed  which  can- 
not be  with  E. 

From  these  observations,  then,  it  is  shown  that 
6.  Recapituia-         syllogism  arises  ;  but  if  B  and  F  are  contraries, 

tion.  jo  '  ....  .      TT 

B  must  necessarily  be  identical  with  a  certain  H, 
and  a  syllogism  arises  through  these.  Nevertheless  it  occurs 
to  persons  thus  inspecting,  that  they  look  to  a  different  way 
than  the  necessary,  from  the  identity  of  B  and  H  escaping 
them. 

Chap.  XXIX.— The  same  Method  applied  to  other  than  cate- 
gorical Syllogisms. 

'  _  Syllogisms  which  lead  to  the  impossible  subsist 

1.  The  same  ,  r„         ,  , 

method  to  be  in  the  same  manner  as  ostensive,  tor  these  also 
"electing  a*  ar*se  through  consequents,  and  those  (antecedents) 
middle  term  in  which  each  follows,2  and  the  inspection  is  the 
"ytheTrnpos°si-  same  in  both,  for  what  is  ostensively  demonstrated 
hie,"  as  in  the  may  be  ais0  syllogistically  inferred  per  impossi- 
ble, and  through  the  same  terms,  and  what  is  de- 
monstrated per  impossible,  may  be  also  proved  ostensively, 
as  that  A  is  with  no  E.  For  let  it  be  supposed  to  be  with  a  cer- 
tain E,  therefore  since  B  is  with  every  A,  and  A  with  a  certain 
E,  B  also  will  be  with  a  certain  E,  but  it  was  present  with  none  ; 
again,  it  may  be  shown  that  A  is  with  a  certain  E,  for  if  A  is  with 
no  E,  but  E  is  with  every  H,  A  will  be  with  no  H,  but  it  was 
supposed  to  be  with  every  H.  It  will  happen  the  same  in  other 
problems,  for  always  and  in  all  things  demonstration  per  im- 
possibile  will  be  from  consequents,  and  from  those  which  each 
follows.  In  every  problem  also  there  is  the  same  considera- 
tion, whether  a  man  wishes  to  syllogize  ostensively,  or  to  lead 
to  the  impossible,  since  both  demonstrations  are  from  the  same 
terms,  as  for  example,  if  A  were  shown  to  be  with  no  E,  because 
B  happens  to  be  with  a  certain  E,  which  is  impossible,  if  it  is  as- 
sumed that  B  is  with  no  E,  but  with  every  A,  it  is  evident  that 
A  will  be  with  no  E.    Again,  if  it  is  ostensively  collected  that  A 

1  Waitz  incorrectly  reads  E. 

s  i.  e.  the  predicate  and  subject  of  the  question. 


CHAP.  XXIX.]  THE    TRIOR   ANALYTICS.  151 

is  with  no  E,  to  those  who  suppose  that  it  is  with  a  certain  E,  it 
may  be  shown  per  impossible  to  be  with  no  E.  The  like  will 
also  occur  in  other  cases,  for  in  all  we  must  assume  some 
common  term  different  from  the  subject  terms  to  which  there 
will  appertain  a  syllogism  of  the  false,  so  that  this  proposition 
being  converted,1  but  the  other  remaining  the  same,  there  will 
be  an  ostensive  syllogism  through  the  same  terms.  2.  Wherein  the 
But  an  ostensive  syllogism  differs  from  that  per  ;*^^e 
impossibile,  because  in  the  ostensive  both  premises  syllogisms 
are  laid  down  according  to  truth,2  but  in  that  °  er" 
which  leads  to  the  impossible  one  is  laid  down  falsely.3 

These  things  however  will  more  fully  appear  by  what  fol- 
lows, when  we  come  to  speak  of  the  impossible,  for  the  pre- 
sent let  so  much  be  manifest  to  us,  that  both  he  who  wishes 
to  syllogize  ostensively,  and  per  impossibile,  must  observe 
these  things.     In  other  syllogisms  indeed  which  are  hypo- 
thetical, such  as  those  which  are  according  to  transumption, 
or  according  to  quality,  the  consideration  will  be  in  the  sub- 
ject terms,  not  in  the  original  ones,  but  in  those    3  Tliemodeof 
taken  afterwards,  but  the  mode  of  inspection  will   investigation 
be  the  same  ;  but  it  is  necessary  also  to  consider,    ^Xetkais. 
and  distinguish,  in  how  many  ways  hypothetical 
syllogisms  arise. 

Each  problem  then  is  demonstrated  thus,  and  some  of  them 
we  may  infer  syllogistically  after  another  method,  for  example, 
universals  by  an  hypothetical  inspection  of  particulars,  for  if 
C  and  H  are  the  same,  and  if  E  is  assumed  to  be  with  H  alone, 

1  That  is,  the  proposition  being  assumed  contradicting  the  conclusion  of 
the  syllogism  leading  to  the  impossible. — Taylor. 

2  They  are  assumed  as  true,  though  sometimes  false. 

3  As  if  false — to  be  confuted  by  a  conclusive  absurdity.  Compare  the 
23rd  chap,  of  this  book  of  the  Analytics.  In  the  place  just  quoted  the 
to  /iera\a^j8av6/x£vov  is  explained  by  Alexander  as  applying  to  the 
conclusive  expression  of  the  syllogism,  because  it  is  taken  differently  to 
the  manner  in  which  it  was  originally  enunciated,  being  at  first  part  of  a 
conditional  agreement,  and  afterwards  a  categorical  conclusion.  For  this 
reason  the  syllogism  is  here  said  to  be  Kara  fitrd\rj\piv.  Were  it  not  for 
this  authority  it  would  seem  simpler  to  interpret  furdk^ig,  "  change 
of  question."  As  to  the  hypothetical  called  Kara  7roiorijra,  mentioned 
here,  we  have  no  data  for  even  a  plausible  conjecture  — Mansel.  Philo- 
ponus  (Scholia,  p.  17*,  b.  9)  says  it  is  a  syllogism.  U  tov  paWov  7)  Ik 
tov  i)TTov,  7)  Ik  tov  bfioiov.  Vide  Whately's  and  Hill's  Logic.  Waiu 
identities  boih  terms.  See  rol.  i.  156' 


152  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i 

A  will  be  with  every  E  ;  and  again,  if  D  and  H  are  the  same, 
and  E  is  predicated  of  H  alone,  (it  may  be  shown)  that  A  is 
with  no  E.  Wherefore  the  inspection  must  clearly  be  in  this 
way  after  the  same  manner  both  in  the  necessary  and  contin- 
gent, for  the  consideration  is  the  same,  and  the  syllogism  both 
of  the  contingent  and  the  absolute  will  be  through  terms  the 
same  in  order ;  in  the  contingent  however  we  may  assume 
things  which  are  not  with,  but  which  may  be,  for  it  has  been 
shown  that  by  these  a  contingent  syllogism  is  produced,  and 
the  reasoning  is  similar  in  the  case  of  the  other  predications. 
From  what  has  been  said  then  it  appears  not  only  that  it  is 
allowable  for  all  syllogisms  to  be  formed  in  this, 
but  that  they  cannot  be  formed  in  any  other  way, 
for  every  syllogism  has  been  shown  to  originate  through  some 
one  of  the  before-named  figures,  and  these  may  not  be  consti- 
tuted through  any  other  than  the  consequents  and  antecedents 
of  a  thing,  for  from  these  are  the  premises  and  assumption  ©f 
the  middle,  so  that  it  is  not  admissible  that  a  syllogism  should 
be  produced  through  other  things. 

Chap.  XXX. — The  preceding  method  of  Demonstration  applicable 

to  all  Problems. 

1  The  method  The  way  then  of  proceeding  in  all  (problems), 
of  demonstra-  both  in  philosophy  and  in  every  art  and  discipline, 
previously"^11  is  the  same,  for  we  must  collect  about  each  of  them 
applicable  to  ail  those  things  which  are  with,  and  the  subjects 
losophicai  in-  which  they  are  with,  and  be  provided  with  as  many 
quiry"  as  possible  of  these,  considering  them  also  through 

three  terms  in  one  way  subverting,  but  in  another  constructing 
according  to  truth  (we  reason)  from  those  which  are  truly  de- 
scribed to  be  inherent,  but  as  regards  dialectic  syllogisms  (we 
must  reason)  from  probable  propositions.  Now  the  princi- 
ples of  universal  syllogisms  have  been  mentioned,  how  they 
subsist,  and  how  we  must  investigate  them,  that  we  may  not 
direct  our  attention  to  every  thing  which  is  said,  nor  to  con- 
structing and  subverting  the  same  things,  nor  both  construct- 
ing universally  or  particularly,  nor  subverting  wholly  or  par- 
tially, but  look  to  things  fewer  and  definite ;  as  to  each 
however  we  must  make  a  selection,  as  of  good  or  of  science. 
The  peculiar  principles  indeed  in  every  science  are  many, 


CHAP.  XXXI. J  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  153 

hence  it  is  the  province  of  experience  to  deliver   2  Ex  erience 
the  principles  of  every  thing,  for  instance,  I  say   is  to  supply  the 
that  astrological  experience  gives  the  principles   demonstration 
of  astrological  science,  for  from  phenomena  being   m  every  sd- 
sufficiently  assumed,  astrological  demonstrations 
have  thus  been  invented,  so  also  is  it  in  every  other  art  and 
science.     Wherefore  if  things  are  assumed  which  exist  in  in- 
dividuals, it  is  now  our  duty  readily  to  exhibit  demonstrations, 
for  if  as  regards  history  nothing  is  omitted  of  what  is  truly 
present  with  things,  we  shall  be  able  about  every  thing  of 
which  there  is  demonstration  to  discover  and  demonstrate  this, 
and  to  make  that  clear  which  is  naturally  incapable  of  demon- 
Station.  ~  ,3.  The  end  of 

Universally  then  we  have  nearly  shown  how  analytical  in- 
propositions  ought  to  be  selected,  but  we  have  efucidate°sub0 
discussed  this  accurately  in  the  treatise  on  Dia-  jects  naturally 

...  J  abstruse. 

lectic.1 

Chap.  XXXI.—  Upon  Divisioyi ;  and  its  Imperfection  as  to  De- 
monstration? 

That  the  division  through  genera3  is  but  a  cer- 
tain small  portion  of  the  method  specified,  it  is  l.'^VuVon,  its 
easy  to  perceive,  for  division  is,  as  it  were,  a  weak  ^argumenTit 
syllogism,  since  it  begs  what  it  ought  to  demonstrate,  is  a  species  of 

1  In  the  Topics.  The  dialectic  however  of  Aristotle,  as  enunciated 
here,  differs  from  that  art  as  exhibited  in  the  Topics,  in  that  he  discusses 
it  in  the  Analytics  as  a  mere  formal  method  of  reasoning,  but  in  the 
Topics  he  gives  it  an  entirely  material  character.  The  dialectic  of  Plato 
corresponds  more  nearly  with  the  metaphysics  of  Aristotle  :  again,  the 
dialectic  of  Aristotle  is  an  art,  but  his  analytic  a  science  ;  see  note  on 
Top.  i.  1. 

2  Vide  Whately,  b.  iii.  sect.  11. 

3  i.  e.  by  which  genera  are  divided  into  species  by  the  addition  of  differ- 
ences. Plato  used  division  as  a  means  of  demonstrating  definitions,  and 
the  utility  of  them,  according  to  Aristotle,  consists  in  employing  them  as 
tests  of  definitions  when  obtained.  Amongst  the  later  Peripatetics,  di- 
vision rose  in  estimation,  and  Andronicus  Rhodius  composed  a  treatise 
on  the  subject.  Modern  logicians  have  chiefly  drawn  from  Boethius' 
work  de  Divistone.  Compare  Top.  vi.  2.  Dichotomy,  or  the  division  al- 
luded to  above  of  genus,  is  approved  by  Aristotle  when  effected  by  con- 
traries, but  not  by  contradictories.  Compare  Eth.  Nic.  vii.  6;  tvaut, 
Logic,  sect.  113;  Trend.  Elem.  sect.  5» ;  also  Categor.  10. 


154  atustoti.e's  organon.  [book  I. 

weak  syiio-  an(j  alwayS  infers  something  of  prior  matter.1 
Now  this  has  first  escaped  the  notice  of  all  those 
who  use  it,  and  they  endeavour  to  show  that  demonstration 
about  essence  and  the  very  nature  of  a  thing  is  possible,  so 
that  they  neither  perceive  that  those  who  divide  happen  to 
syllogize,  nor  that  it  is  possible  in  the  manner  we  have  said. 
In  demonstrations  therefore,  when  it  is  requisite  to  infer  ab- 
solute presence,  the  middle  term  by  which  the  syllogism  is 
2  in  demon-  produced  must  always  be  less,  and  must  not  be 
stmtion  of  the  universally  predicated  of  the  first  extreme,  but  on 
middle  must  the  contrary,  division  takes  the  universal  for  the 
be  less,  and  not   middle  term.     For  let  animal  be  A,  mortal  B,  im- 

umversal  in  re-  _  _       , 

spect  of  the  first   mortal  b,  and  man  ot  whom  we  ought  to  assume 
extreme.  ^q  definition  D,  every  animal  then  comprehends 

either  mortal  or  immortal,  but  this  is  that  the  whole  of  what- 
ever may  be  A  is  either  B  or  C.  Again,  he  who  divides 
man,  admits  that  he  is  animal,  so  that  he  assumes  A  to  be 
predicated  of  D,  hence  the  syllogism  is  that  every  D  is  either 
B  or  C,  wherefore  it  is  necessary  for  man  to  be  either  mortal 
or  immortal,  yet  it  is  not  necessary  that  animal  should  be 
mortal,  but  this  is  desired  to  be  granted,  which  was  the  very 
thing  which  ought  to  have  been  syllogistically  in- 
ferred.* Again,  taking  A  for  mortal  animal,  B 
for  pedestrian,  C  without  feet,  and  D  for  man,  in  the  same 
manner  it  assumes  A  to  be  either  with  B  or  C,  for  every  mortal 
animal  is  either  pedestrian  or  without  feet,  and  that  A  is  pre- 
dicated of  D,  for  it  has  assumed  that  man  is  a  mortal  animal, 
so  that  it  is  necessary  that  man  should  be  either  a  pedestrian 

1  i.  e.  of  universals,  or  of  things  more  nearly  approaching  to  these. 

Ex.  1.  Every  animal  is  either  mortal  or  immortal. 
Every  man  is  an  animal 
.  • .  Every  man  is  either  mortal  or  immortal. 

The  conclusion  here  was  to  have  been,  that  every  man  is  mortal ;  but  he 
who  divides  does  not  prove  this,  but  desires  it  to  be  granted. 

Ex.  2.  Every  mortal  animal  is  pedestrian  or  without  feet 
Every  man  is  a  mortal  animal 
.  * .  Every  roan  is  pedestrian  or  without  feet. 

Ex.  3.  Every  length  is  or  is  not  commensurable 
Every  diameter  is  a  length 
. '  .  Every  diameter  is  or  is  not  commensurable. 


CHAP.  XXXII.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  15-5 

animal  or  without  feet,  but  that  he  is  pedestrian  is  not  neces- 
sary, but  they  assume  it,  and  this  again  is  what      _        ,  ,„ 

i  i  i  i**ci-  *  Example  2.) 

they  ought  to  have  proved.  Alter  tins  manner 
it  always  happens  to  those  who  divide,  namely,  that  they  as- 
sume an  universal  middle,  and  what  they  ought  to  show,  and 
the  differences  as  extremes.  In  the  last  place,  they  assert 
nothing  clearly,  as  that  it  is  necessary  that  this  be  a  man,  or 
that  the t  question  necessarily  is  whatever  it  may        ,  „     . 

,  ,  '     n  *,  ^       T  to  In  rou  ue- 

be,  but  they  pursue  every  other  way,  not  appre-    vo*.    (Vjje 
bending  the  available  supplies.     It  is  clear  how-    ^"^vision  not 
ever,  that  by  this  method  we  can  neither  subvert   suitable  for  re- 
nor  syllogistically  infer  any  thing  of  accident  or   for  various0 
property  or  genus,  or  of  those  things  of  which  we   ^.inds  of  iues- 
are  a  priori  ignorant  as   to  how  they  subsist,  as 
whether  the  diameter  of  a  square  be  incommensurable,  for  if 
it  assumes  every  length  to  be  either  commensurable  or  incom- 
mensurable, but  the  diameter  of  a  square  is  a  length,  it  will 
infer  that  the  diameter  is  either  incommensurable  or  com- 
mensurable, and  if  it  assumes  that  it  is  incommensurate,  it  will 
assume  what  it  ought  to  prove,   wherefore  that  we   cannot 
show,  for  this  is  the  way,  and  by  this  we  cannot  do  it ;  let 
however  the  incommensurable  or  commensurable  be  A,  length 
B,  and  diameter  C.J     It  is  clear  then  that  this    4  _        ,  ,„' 

'    ,        n  ■  ■        A    +  ,    .•  t  Example  (3.) 

mode  oi  inquiry  does  not  suit  every  speculation, 
neither  is  useful  in  those  to  which  it  especially  appears  ap- 
propriate, wherefore  from  what  sources,  and  how  demonstra- 
tions arise,  and  what  we  must  regard  in  every  problem,  appear 
from  what  has  been  said. 


Chap.  XXXII. — Reduction  of  Syllogisms  to  the  above  Figures? 

How  then  we  may  reduce  syllogisms  to  the  above-  j  Method  of 

named  figures  must  next  be  told,  for  this  is  the  reducing  every 

remainder  of  the  speculation,  since  if  we  have  one  of  the  three 

noticed  the  production  of  syllogisms,  and  have  the  *«««*  t0}e 

.    r        .  ,  ."V.  considered. 

power  of  inventing  them,  it  moreover  we  analyze    (Compare  ch. 
them  when  formed  into  the  before-named  figures,   28-) 

1  Averrois  commences  his  third  section  here,  "  de  syllogismorum  reso- 
lutions."  The  word  dvdytiv,  and  not  ciTrayiiv,  as  significative  of  reduction, 
has  been  already  commented  upon  ;  it  is  employed  in  its  strict  meaning  at 
this  place. 


156  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  l 

our  original  design  will  have  been  completed.     At  the  same 

time,  what  has  before  been  said  will  happen  to  be  confirmed, 

and  be  more  evident  that  they  are  thus  from  what  shall  now 

be  said,  for  every  truth  must  necessarily  agree  with  itself  in 

every  respect. 

Rule  1st.  First  then  we  must  endeavour  to  select  the  two 

Propositions  to   propositions  of  a  syllogism,  for  it  is  easier  to  di- 
ce investigated    x  .    l     .  i  •  1 

as  to  quantity,  vide  into  greater  than  into  less  parts,1  and  com- 
posites are  greater  than  the  things  of  which  they 
are  composed  ;  next  we  must  consider  whether  it  is  in  a  whole 
or  in  a  part,  and  if  both  propositions  should  not  be  assumed, 
oneself  placing  one  of  them.  For  those  who  propose  the  uni- 
versal2 do  not  receive  the  other  which  is  contained  in  it,3 
neither  when  they  write,  nor  when  they  interrogate,  or  pro- 
pose these,4  but  omit  those5  by  which  these  are  concluded, 
and  question  other  things  to  no  purpose.  There- 
Examine  their  f°re  we  must  consider  whether  any  thing  super- 
superfluities       fluous  has  been  assumed,  and  any  thing:  necessary 

and  deficiencies  .        ,  .  ,.  .  i        1    • -i     -i  ■% 

as  to  the  proper  omitted,  and  one  thing  is  to  be  laid  down,  and 
syllogism!0"  °f  anotuer  to  be  removed,  until  we  arrive  at  two 
propositions,  for  without  these  we  cannot  reduce 
the  sentences  which  are  thus  the  subjects  of  question.  Now 
in  some  it  is  easy  to  see  what  is  deficient,  but  others  escape 
us,  and  seem  to  be  syllogisms,6  because  something  necessarily 
happens  from  the  things  laid  down,  as  if  it  should  be  assumed 
that  essence  not  being  subverted,  essence  is  not  subverted,7 
but  those  things  being  subverted,  of  which  a  thing  consists, 
what  is  composed  of  these  is  subverted  also ;  for  from  these 

1  i.  e.  into  propositions  than  into  terms. 

*  i.  e.  the  major  proposition,  which  is  always  universal  in  the  first 
figure. 

3  i.  e.  the  minor,  which  stands  towards  the  major  in  the  relation  of 
particular  to  universal. 

4  i.  e.  the  propositions  of  the  principal  syllogism. 

5  i.  e.  the  propositions  of  the  pro-syllogism.  This  last  is  the  antece- 
dent in  a  minor  premise,  which  makes  it  enthymematic.  Vide  Whately, 
book  ii.  eh.  4,  sect.  7,  note. 

9  Vide  Whately's  table  of  Fallacies,  book  iii. 

7  In  the  propositions  adduced,  the  syllogistic  form  is  not  present,  but 
syllogistic  inferences  may  be  derived  from  them.  In  the  place  of  the 
major,  we  have  an  equivalent  proposition  expressed,  and  in  place  of  the 
minor — the  major  of  the  pro-syllogism  proving  that  nrnor  is  added;  this 
major,  however,  is  changed  so  far,  as  it  is  made  more 


CHAP.  XXXII.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS*  57 

positions  it  is   necessary  that  a  part  of  essence  should  be 
essence,  yet  this  is  not  concluded  through  the  assumptions, 
but  the  propositions  are  wanting.     Again,  if  because  man  ex- 
ists, it  is  necessary  that  animal  should  be,  and  animal  exist- 
ing, that  there  should  be  essence  ;   then,  because   ^  ^ 
man  exists,  essence  must  necessarily  be  ;  but  this   consider  the 
is  not  yet  syllogistically  inferred,1  for  the  proposi-   ™iity  °f  infer" 
tions  do  not  subsist  as  we  have  said  they  should  ; 2 
but  we  are  deceived  in  such,  because  something  necessary 
happens  from  the  things  laid  down,  and  because  also  a  syllo- 
gism is   something   necessary.     The  necessary,   however,   is 
more  extensive  than  the  syllogism,  for  every  syllogism  is  ne- 
cessary, but  not  every  thing  necessary  is  a  syllogism ;  so  that 
if  any  thing  occurs  from  certain  positions,  we  must  not  imme- 
diately endeavour  to  reduce,  but  first  assume  two  propositions, 
then  we  must  divide  them  into  terms,  in  this  manner,  that 
term  we  must  place  as  the  middle  which  is  said  to  be  in  both 
propositions,  for  the  middle  must  necessarily  exist  in  both,  in 
all  the  figures.     If  then   the  middle  predicates, 
and  is  predicated  of,  or  if  it  indeed  predicates,    Ascertata  the 
but  another  thing  is  denied  of  it,  there  will  be  the   JsjJ£rg  t^ich 
first  figure,  but  if  it  predicates,  and  is  denied  by   problem  be- 
something,  there  will  be  the  middle  figure,  and  if  J^dsdsieby  the 
other  things  are  predicated  of  it,  and  one  thing  is 
denied,  but  another  is  predicated,  there  will  be  the  last  figure  ; 
thus  the  middle  subsists  in  each  figure.     In  a  similar  manner 
also,  if  the  propositions  should  not  be  universal,  for  the  deter- 
mination of  the  middle  is  the  same,3  wherefore  it  is  evident, 
that  in  discourse,  where  the  same  thing  is  not  asserted  more 
than  once,  a  syllogism  does  not  subsist,  since  the  middle  is 
not  assumed.     As,  however,  we  know  what  kind  of  problem 
is  deduced  in  each  figure,4  in  what  the  universal,  and  in  what 
the  particular,  it  is  clear  that  we  must  not  regard  all  the 
figures,  but  that  one  which  is  appropriate  to  each  problem, 
and  whatever  things  are  deduced  in  many  figures,  we  may 
ascertain  the  figure  of  by  the  position  of  the  middle. 

1  i.  e.  it  is  not  categorical,  but  hypothetical. 

2  They  neither  affirm  nor  deny. 

3  For  an  universal  does  not  differ  from  a  particular,  by  reason  of  the 
middle  term,  but  by  the  circumscription  and  determination  of  the  verbal 
sign,  "every,"  "none,"  called  Trpoadiopia^o^.  See  Hill's  Logic,  and 
Whately.  *  From  chapter  26. 


158  aristotle's  organon.  [book  t. 


Chap.  XXXIII. — On  Error,  arising  from  the  quantity  of 
Propositions. 

i.  cause  of  de-  It  frequently  happens  then,  that  we  are  deceived 
wftagtam!-^1  about  syllogisms,  on  account  of  the  necessary 
our  inattention   (conclusion),  as  we  have  before  observed,  and  some- 

to  the  relative  .  . 

quantity  of  times  by  the  resemblance1  in  the  position  of  the 
propositions.       terms,  which  ought  not  to  have  escaped  us. 

Thus  if  A  is  predicated  of  B,  and  B  of  C,  there  would 
appear  a  syllogism  from  such  terms,  yet  neither  is  any  thing 
necessary  produced,  nor  a  syllogism.  For  let  A  be  that  which 
always  is ;  B,  Aristomenes  the  object  of  intellect ;  and  C, 
Aristomenes  ;  it  is  true  then  that  A  is  with  B,  for  Aristomenes 
is  always  the  object  of  intellect ;  but  B  is  also  with  C,  for  Aristo- 
menes is  Aristomenes  the  object  of  intellect,  but  A  is  not  with 
C,  for  Aristomenes  is  corruptible,  neither  would  a  syllogism 
be  formed  from  terms  thus  placed,  but  the  universal  proposi- 
tion2 A  B  must  be  assumed,  but  this  is  false,3  to  think  that 
every  Aristomenes  who  is  the  object  of  intellect  always  exists, 
when  Aristomenes  is  corruptible.  Again,  let  C  be  Miccalus, 
B  Miccalus  the  musician,  A  to  die  to-morrow ;  B  therefore  is 
truly  predicated  of  C,  since  Miccalus  is  Miccalus  the  musician, 
and  A  is  truly  predicated  of  B,  for  Miccalus  the  musician  may 
die  to-morrow,  but  A  is  falsely  predicated  of  C.  This  case 
therefore  is  the  same  with  the  preceding,  for  it  is  not  uni- 
versally true  that  Miccalus  the  musician  will  die  to-morrow, 
and  if  this  is  not  assumed,  there  would  be  no  syllogism.4 

This  deception  arises  therefore  from  a  small  (matter),  since 
we  concede,  as  if  there  were  no  difference  between  saying 
that  this  thing  is  present  with  that,  and  this  present  with 
evert/  individual  of  that. 

1  In  indefinites,  which  are  mistaken  for  universals. 

2  i.  e.  the  major. 

3  Because  the  distributive  particle  "  every  "  shows  that  any  particular 
is  assumed. 

4  Here  the  fallacy  arises  from  the  major  not  being  universal,  for  it  is 
not  said  that  every  Miccalus,  a  musician,  will  die  to-morrow.  Vide 
Appendix  to  Hill's  Logic. 


CHAP.  XXXIV.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  159 


Chap.  XXXIV. — Error  arising  from  inaccurate  exposition 

of  Terms.1 

Deception  will  frequently  occur  from  the  terms  1.  Nature  of  dv- 
of  the  proposition  being  improperly  expounded,2  2mm„*SSS, 
as  if  A  should  be  health,  B  disease,  and  C  man,  terms  inaccu- 
for  it  is  true  to  say  that  A  cannot  be  with  any  B, 
for  health  is  with  no  disease,  and  again  that  B  is  with  every  C, 
for  every  man  is  susceptible  of  disease,  whence  it  would  appear 
to  result  that  health  can  be  with  no  man.  Now  the  reason  of  this 
is,  that  the  terms  are  not  rightly  set  out  in  expression,  since 
those  words  which  are  significant  of  habits  being  changed, 
there  will  not  be  a  syllogism,  as  if  the  word  "  well "  were 
taken  instead  of  "health,"  and  the  word  "ill"  instead  of  "dis- 
ease," since  it  is  not  true  to  say,  that  to  be  well  cannot  be  pre- 
sent with  him  that  is  ill.  Now  this  not  being  assumed,  there 
is  no  syllogism  except  of  the  contingent,3  which  indeed  is  not 
impossible,  for  health  may  happen  to  be  with  no  man.  Again, 
in  the  middle  figure  there  will  likewise  be  a  falsity,  for  health 
happens  to  be  with  no  disease,  but  may  happen  to  be  with  every 
man,  so  that  disease  shall  be  with  no  man.4  In  the  third  figure 
however  falsity  occurs  by  the  contingent,  for  it  is  possible  that 
health  and  disease,  science  and  ignorance,  in  short,  contraries, 
shall  be  with  the  same  individual,  but  it  is  impossible  that 
they  should  be  present  with  each  other  :  this,  however,  differs 
from  the  preceding  observations,*  since  when  m  y.de  ch 
many  things  happen  to  be  present  with  the  same 
individual  they  also  happen  to  be  so  with  each  other. 

Evidently  then  in  all  these  cases  deception  arises  from  the 
setting  forth  of  the  terms,  as  if  those  are  changed  which  relate 
to  the  habits,  there  is  no  falsity,  and  it  is  therefore  apparent 

1  Vide  Hill,  on  verbal  and  material  fallacy;  also  Whately,  who  refers 
the  Aristotelian  division  of  fallacies  (oi  irapa.  ti)v  \e£iv  and  oi  t£w  Tr";c 
\e£iwQ)  to  logical  and  material,  upon  a  species  of  conjecture.  Confer. 
Waitz,  vol.  ii.  p.  532. 

2  Because  an  abstract  term,  "health,"  is  assumed  for  a  concrete,  as 
"sane." 

3  For  a  man  now  ill,  may  not  hereafter  be  well ;  that  to  be  ill  is  pre- 
sent with  every  man,  therefore  to  be  well  present  with  no  man. 

4  This  is  against  the  rule  laid  down  in  ch.  2,  of  the  next  book,  wherein 
he  shows  that  the  false  cannot  be  collected  from  the  true. 


160  auisioxle's  organon.  [book  I. 

that  in  such  propositions,  what  relates  to  hat  it1  must  always 
be  exchanged  and  placed  for  a  term  instead  of  habit.2 

Chap.  XXXV. — Middle  not  always  to  be  assumed  as  a  particular 
definite  thing,  wc  roSt  ri. 

i.  One  word  ^T  *s  not  always  necessary  to  seek  to  expound  the 

cannot  always  terms  by  a  name,3  since  there  will  oftentimes  be 

someeterms,in-  sentences  to  which  no  name  is  attached,  wherefore 

asmuchasthey  it  is  difficult  to  reduce  syllogisms  of  this  kind, 

are  sentences.      ■,  in  ■■  •  ,-..,. 

but  we  shall  sometimes  happen  to  be  deceived  by 
such  a  search,  for  example,  because  a  syllogism  is  of  things  im- 
mediate.4 For  let  A5  be  two  right  angles,  B  a  triangle,  C  an 
isosceles  triangle.  A  then  is  with  C  through  B,  but  no  longer 
with  B  through  any  thing  else,  for  a  triangle  has  of  itself  two 
right  angles,  so  that  there  will  not  be  a  middle  of  the  propo- 
sition A  B,6  which  is  demonstrable.  The  middle  then  must 
clearly  not  thus  be  always  assumed,  as  if  it  were  a  particular 
definite  thing,7  but  sometimes  a  sentence,  which  happens  to  be 
the  case  in  the  instance  adduced. 


Chap.  XXXVI. — On  the  arrangement  of  Terms,  according  to  nomi- 
nal appellation  ;  and  of  Propositions  according  to  case.* 

1.  For  the  con-   For  the  first  to  be  in  the  middle,  and  the  latter 

structionofa  .»  .  •.     •  .  „ 

syllogism,  it  is  m  tlie  extreme,  it  is  unnecessary  to  assume  as  if 
not  always  re-  they  were  always  predicated  of  each  other,  or  in 
term  should  be   like  manner,9  the  first  cf  the  middle,  and  this  in 

1  The  concrete  word  "well." 

2  The  abstract,  "  health."  3  One  word. 

4  Between  which  there  is  no  middle — they  may  be  proved,  however, 
by  a  definition  of  the  subject,  as  in  the  Post  Ana.  Vide  Pacius  and 
Biese,  vol.  i.  p.  157;  also  Aquinas,  Op.  48.  cap.  1.  The  word  dfitffoc  is 
used  by  Aristotle,  either  to  express  a  proposition  not  proved  by  any 
higher  middle  term,  (vide  An.  Post,  i.  2,  and  ii.  19,)  or  a  premise  imme- 
diate, as  regards  its  conclusion,  i.  e.  not  requiring  the  insertion  of  lower 
middle  terms,  for  connexion  of  its  terms  withthose  of  the  conclusion. 

3  i.  e.  three  angles,  equal  to  two  right. 

6  A  certain  middle  thing,  signified  by  one  word. 

7  As  one  thing  expressed  by  one  word. 

g  Aristotle  distinguishes  KXijang  and  tttwvuc,  (which  last  word  he  uses 
for  rponoQ,)  the  first  as  being  nouns  in  the  nominatire  case,  the  other  the 
oblique  cases.    See  Hcrmen.  c.  2.  9  i.  e.  in  the  same  case. 


CHAP.  XXXVI.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  161 

the  last,  and  also  likewise  in  the  case  of  non-  predicated  of 
inesse.  Still  in  so  many  ways  as  to  be  is  predi-  »casu recto." 
cated,  and  any  thins;  is  truly  asserted,  it  is  requi-   Since  either 

.  i         i  .       .P       .       .  .  major  or  minor 

site  to  consider  that  we  signify  the  inesse,  as  that  premise,  or 
of  contraries  there  is  one  science.  an^obHque^6 

For  let  A  be,  there  is  one  science,  and  B,  things  case, 
contrary  to  each  other,  A  then  is  present  with  B,  not  as  if 
contraries  are  one  science,1  but  because  it  is  true  in  respect  of 
them,  to  say  that  there  is  one  science  of  them.  It  sometimes 
occurs  indeed,  that  the  first  is  predicated  of  the  middle,  but 
the  middle  not  of  the  third,  as  if  wisdom  is  science,  but 
wisdom  is  of'2  good,  the  conclusion  is  that  science  is  of  good : 
hence  good  is  not  wisdom,  but  wisdom  is  science.  Some- 
times, again,  the  middle  is  predicated  of  the  third,  but  the  first 
not  of  the  middle,  e.  g.  if  there  is  a  science  of  every  quality 
or  contrary,  hut  good  is  a  contrary  and  a  quality,  the  con- 
clusion then  is,  that  there  is  a  science  of  good,  yet  neither 
good,  nor  quality,  nor  contrary  is  science,  but  good  is  these.3 
Sometimes,  again,  neither  the  first  is  predicated  of  the  middle, 
nor  this  of  the  third,  the  first  indeed  being  sometimes  predi- 
cated of  the  third,  and  sometimes  not,4  for  instance,  of  whatever 
there  is  science,  there  is  genus,  but  there  is  science  of  good, 
the  conclusion  is  that  there  is  a  genus  of  good,  yet  none  of 
these  is  predicated  of  any.  If,  nevertheless,  of  what  there  is 
science,  this  is  genus,  but  there  is  a  science  of  good,  the  con- 
clusion is  that  good  is  genus,  hence  the  first  is  predicated  of 
the  extreme,  but  there,  is  no  predication  of  each  other.5 

In  the  case  of  the  non-inesse  there  must  be  the  2  Method  the 
same  manner  of  assumption,  for  this  thing  not  same  with  ne- 
being  present  with  this,  does  not  always  signify  ga  lve 
that  this  is  not  this,  but  sometimes  that  this  is  not  of  this,  or 
that  this  is  not  with  this,  as  there  is  not  a  motion  of  motion  or 
generation  of  generation,  but  there  is  (a  motion  and  genera- 
tion) of  pleasure  :  pleasure  therefore  is  not  generation.  Again, 
there  is  of  laughter  a   sign,  but  there   is   not  a  sign  of  a 

1  Waitz  inserts  avrwv.  2  Here  he  also  inserts  t7rio-ri)/u/.  Aristotle 
means,  that  in  the  major  proposition  the  greater  extreme  is  in  a  direct, 
but  in  the  minor  proposition  the  middle  is  in  an  oblique  case. 

3  i.  e.  good  is  a  quality,  and  is  contrary,  hence  the  minor  is  direct. 

4  i.  e.  "  recta  predicatione."    Buhle. 

1   The  conclusion  ia  direct,  but  the  propositions  are  oblique. 

in 


162  aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

sign,  so  that  laughter  is  not  a  sign,  and  similarly  in  other 
cases,  wherein  the  problem  is  subverted  from  the  genus  being 
in  some  way  referred  to  it.1  Moreover,  occasion  is  not  oppor- 
tune time,  for  to  the  divinity  there  is  occasion,  but  not  oppor- 
tune time,  because  there  is  nothing  useful  to  divinity,2  we 
must  take  as  terms,  occasion,  opportune  time,  and  divinity, 
but  the  proposition  must  be  assumed  according  to 

3.  Method  of        , ,  <•  f .  •  ,  .  *?,  • 

assuming  pro-  the  case  ot  the  noun,  since,  in  short,  we  assert  this 
positions  and  universally,  that  we  must  always  place  the  terms 
according  to  the  appellations  of  the  nouns,  e.  g. 
man,  or  good,  or  contraries,  not  of  man,  nor  of  good,  nor  of 
contraries,  but  we  must  take  propositions  according  to  the  cases 
of  each  word,  since  they  are  either  to  this  as  the  equal,  or  of 
this  as  the  double,  or  this  thing  as  striking,  or  seeing,  or  this 
one  as  man,  animal,  or  if  the  noun  falls  in  any  other  way,  ac- 
cording to  the  proposition. 

Chap.   XXXVII. — Rules  of  Reference  to  the  forms  of  Predication. 

For  this  thing  to  be  with  that,  and  for  one  thing 
absoiuteUpredi-  to  he  truly  predicated  of  another,  must  be  assumed 
acte°ntThe^eSt  *n  as  man7  wavs  as  the  categories  are  divided  ;  the 
verai  varieties  latter  must  also  be  taken  either  in  a  certain  re- 
divTslon0™1'      spec*?3  or  simply,  moreover  either  as  simple  4  or 

connected,5  in  a  similar  manner  also  with  regard 
to  the  non-inesse  ;  these  however  must  be  better  considered 
and  denned. 

1  Either  directly  or  obliquely.  Aristotle  calls  the  middle  term  in  the 
second  figure,  genus,  because  as  the  latter  is  predicated,  the  middle  term 
in  the  second  figure  is  also  predicated ;  otherwise  they  differ  greatly,  since 
genus  is  predicated  of  species  affirmatively,  but  the  middle  in  the  second 
figure  is  partly  predicated  affirmatively,  and  partly  negatively,  since  one 
premise  ought  to  affirm,  and  the  other  deny. 

2  This  syllogism  is  in  the  third  figure ;  the  middle  term  being 
"  divinity." 

s  As,  an  Ethiopian  has  white  teeth. 

4  As,  a  swan  is  an  animal. 

*  As.  a  swan  is  a  white  animal. 


CHAP    XXXVIII.]       THE   PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  163 


Chap.  XXXVIII. — Of  Propositional  Iteration  and  the  Addition 

to  a  Predicate. 

Whatever  is  reiterated*1  in  propositions  must 

be  annexed  to  the  major  and  not  to  the  middle  *  t*avai,*\oir 

term  ;  I  mean  for  instance,  if  there  should  be  a 

syllogism,  that  there  is   a  science  of  justice  "because   it  is 

good,"  the  expression  "  because  it  is  good,"  or  "  in   j  whatever  is 

that  it  is  good,"  must  be  joined  to  the  major.  For  reiterated 

let  A  be  "science,  that  it  is  good  ;"  B,  "good  ;"   "dto theinqjor* 

and  C,  "justice  ;"  A  then  is  truly  predicated  of  not  to  the  mid' 

B,  since  of  good  there  is  science  that  it  is  good  : 

but  B  is  also  true  of  C  ;  for  justice  is  what  is  good,  thus 

therefore  the  solution  is  made.t     But  if,  "  that  it    ,  „ 

,  „  ,  ,  ,     ,  -r»  o  •,        -li  i  n  <  Example  (1.) 

is  good     be  added  to  B,2  it  will  not  be  true  ;  for 

A  will  indeed  be  truly  predicated  of  B,  but  it  will  not  be 

true  that  B  is  predicated  of  C,  since  to  predicate  of  justice, 

good  that  it  is  good,  is  false,  and  not  intelligible.      So  also  it 

may  be  shown  that  the  healthy  is  an  object  of  science  in  that 

it  is  good,  or  that  hircocervus  is  an  object  of  opinion,  quoad 

its  nonentity,3  or  that  man  is  corruptible,  so  far  as 

he  is  sensible,  for  in  all  super-predications,  we  t*'«a-m-yopoZ- 

must  annex  the  repetition  to  the  (major)  term. 

1  tirav.  dicitur  in  oratione,  quod  accedit,  praesertim  si  ita  accedit  ut 
sensus  aut  leviter,  aut  omnino  non  mutetur.  Waitz.  A  syllogism  is  how- 
ever said  to  be  produced  fitra  7rpoo-0/jic?jc,  when  something  is  added  to 
the  predicate,  to  tTriicarriyopovfitvov. 

Ex.  1.  Of  good  there  is  science  that  it  is  good 
Justice  is  good 
.  • .  Of  justice  there  is  science  that  it  is  good. 
J  That  is,  to  the  middle. 

3  An  animal  formed  from  the  union  of  a  goat  and  a  stag.  The  syllogism 
may  be  thus  constructed. 

Non-being  is  an  object  of  opinion  quoad  nonentity 
An  hircocervus  is  a  nonentity 
.  • .  An  hircocervus  is  an  object  of  opinion  quoad  nonentity. 

Ex.  2.  Every  being  is  an  object  of  science 
Good  is  being 
.  •.   Good  is  an  object  of  science. 
Ex.  3.   Of  being  there  is  science,  that  it  is  being 
Good  is  being 
.  •  .    Of  good  there  is  science,  that  it  is  being. 

m  2 


164  arijtotle's  org  anon.  [book  t. 

The  position  of  the  terms  is  nevertheless  not 

2.  The  terms  r     ■  .  „      .     .      ln      .    c  , 

not  the  same  the  same  when  a  thing  is  syllogistically  interred 
t?onThXPr"  simply,  and  when  this  particular  thing,  or  in  a 
the  inference  is  certain  respect,  or  in  a  certain  way.  For  instance, 
a  cenain'quaii-  I  mean,  as  when  good  is  shown  to  be  an  object  of 
ncation.  science,  and  when  it  is  shown  to  be  so  because  it  is 

"ood ;  but  if  it  is  shown  to  be  an  object  of  science  simply,  we 
must  take  "  being  "  as  the  middle  term  ;  *  if  (it  is 
*  Example  (2.)   prove(j  that  it  may  be  scientifically  known)  to  be 

good,  a  certain  being  (must  be  taken  as  the  middle).  For 
let  A  be  "  science,  that  it  is  a  certain  being,"  B  "  a  certain 
being,"  and  C  "  good  ; "  to  predicate  then  A  of  B  is  true, 
for  there  is  science  of  a  certain  being,  that  it  is  a  certain 
bein"- ;  but  B  is  also  predicated  of  C,  because  C  is  a  cer- 
tain being  ;  f  therefore  A  will  be  predicated  of  C, 
t 1.  e.  good.  jience  there  will  be  science  of  good  that  it  is  good, 
for  the  expression  "a  certain  being"  is  the  sign  of  peculiar 
or  proper  essence.  If,  on  the  other  hand,  "  being  "  is  set  as 
the  middle,  and  being  simply  and  not  a  certain  being  is  added 
to  the  extreme,  there  will  not  be  a  syllogism  that  there  is  a 
science  of  good,  that  it  is  good,  but  that  it  is  being  :  for  ex- 
ample, let  A  be  science  that  it  is  being  ;  B,  being  ; 
t  Example  (3.)   ^  ^  good;j.  In  guch  Syii0gisiiis  then  as  are  from 

a  part,1  we  must  clearly  take  the  terms  after  this  manner. 

Chap.  XXXIX.— The  Simplification  of  Terms  in  the  Solution  of 

Syllogism. 

We  must  also  exchange  those  which  have  the  same  import  ; 

nouns  for  nouns,  and  sentences  for  sentences,  and  a  noun  and 

a  sentence,2  and  always  take  the  noun  for  the  sentence,  for 

thus  the  exposition  of  the  terms  will  be  easier.     For  example, 

l.  in  syiio-       if  there  is  no  difference  in  saying  that  what  is 

gistic  analysis     supposed  is  not  the  genus  of  what  is  opined,  or  that 

piidty  and  per-  what  is  opined  is  not  any  thing  which  may  be 

spicuitytobe     supPosed,  (for  the  signification  is  the  same,)  in- 
studied,  tfr        n     ■>  11  1 

stead  ot  the  sentence  already  expressed  we  must 

1  "Ev  fitpti  vocat  eos  qui  noil  anXwg  ri  sed  rode  n  concludunt.  Waitz. 
Vide  Biese,  i.  p.  179,  not.  2. 

-  Either  for  either.  This  is  omitted  by  Taylor,  though  read  by  Averrois, 
Buhle,  Waitz.  This  direction,  except  carefully  done,  gives  rise  to  frequent 
fallacies.  Quando  pro  termino  repetendo,  substituitur  vox  illi  aequipol- 
lens.  Aldrich.  Whately  on  Fallacies. 


CHAP.  XL.  XLI.]        THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS  165 

take  what  may   be  supposed  and  what  may  be  opined,  as 
terms. 

Chap.  XL. — Tlxe  definite  Article  to  be  added  according  to  the  nature 

of  the  Conclusion. 

Since  however  it  is  not  the  same,  for  pleasure  to 

be  good,  and  for  pleasure  to  be  the  good,  we  must   Idd^tTraof  the* 

not  set  the  terms  alike  ;  but  if  there  is  a  syllogism   axi^,  and 

that  pleasure  is  the  good,  the  good  (must  be  taken 

as  a  term)  if  that  it  is  good,  good  (must  be  taken),  and  so  of 

the  rest. 


Chap.  XLI. — On  the  Distinction  of  certain  forms  of  Universal 

Predication. 

It  is  neither  in  fact  nor  in  word  the  same  thing   ,   The  expres. 


to  assert  that  A  is  present  with  every  individual  sionKae' ovjob 

with  which  B  is  present,  and  to  say  that  A  is  T\%*at>!i°? T 

present  with  every  individual  of  what  B  is  pre-  pe^f^nticai 

sent   with,  since    there    is   nothing  to    prevent  with  «a(fot 

B  from   being  with  C,  yet  not  with  every  C.1  ™l\*0£r* 

For  instance,  let  B  be  beautiful,  but  C  white,  if  r<*«-°f"»™A, 

,  ,  •<•  i    •  •  i  .  -i  ■         •     •  is  equivalent 

then  beautiful  is  with  something  white,  it  is  true  to  a  being  pre- 
to  say  that  beauty  is  present  with  what  is  Avhite,  everything  of 
yet  not  perhaps  with  every  thing  white.  If  then  w.nicn  B  is  pre- 
A  is  with  B,  but  not  with  every  thing  of  which 
B  is  predicated,  neither  if  B  is  present  with  every  C,  nor  if 
it  is  alone  present,  it  is  necessary  that  A  should  not  only  not 
be  present  with  every  C,  but  that  it  should  not  be  present 
(at  all),  but  if  that  of  which  B  is  truly  predicated,  with  every 
individual  of  this  A  is  present,  it  will  happen  that  A  will  be 
predicated  of  every  individual  of  which  B  is  predicated  of 
every  individual.  But  if  A  is  predicated  of  that  of  which  B 
is  universally  predicated,  there  is  nothing  to  prevent  B  from 
being  present  with  C  with  not  every  or  with  no  individual  of 
which  A  is  present,  therefore  in  (three  terms  it  is  evident 
that)  the  assertion  that  A  is  predicated  of  every  individual  of 
which  B  is  predicated,  signifies  that  of  whatever  B  is  prcdi- 

1  Therefore  "  that  with  'which  B   is  present,"  and  "  that  with  every 
individual  of  which  B  is  present,"  do  not  mean  the  same  thing. 


166  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

cated  of  all  these  A  is  predicated  also,  and  if  B  is  predicated 
of  every,  A  will  also  thus  be  predicated,  but  if  it  is  not 
predicated  of  every  individual  it  is  not  necessary  that  A  should 
be  predicated  of  every  individual. 

Still  we  need  not  imagine  that  any  absurdity  will  occur 
from  this  exposition,  for  we  do  not  use  the  expression  that 
this  is  a  particular  definite  thing,1  but  as  a  geometrician  says 
that  this  is  a  foot  in  length,  is  a  straight  line,  and  is  without 
breadth  though  it  is  not  so,  he  does  not  however  so  use  them, 
as  if  he  inferred  2  from  these.  In  a  word,  that  which  is  not 
2.  certain  ex-  as  a  whole  to  a  part,  and  something  else  in  refer- 
pressions  used    ence  to  this  as  a  part  to  a  whole,  from  nothing  of 

for  illustration.     ,,  -,  ,  ,° 

these  can  a  demonstrator  demonstrate,  where- 
fore neither  is  there  a  syllogism,  but  we  use  exposition  as  we 
do  sense  3  when  we  address  a  learner,  since  we  do  not  (use  it) 
so  as  if  it  were  impossible  to  be  demonstrated  without  these, 
as  (we  use  propositions)  from  which  a  syllogism  is  con- 
structed. 


Chap.  XLII. — That  not  all  Conclusions  in  the  same  Sylloghm  are 
produced  through  one  Figure. 

1  The  conciu-  -^ET  us  not  f°r»et  tnat  a^  conclusions  in  the  same 
sion  an  evi-  syllogism  are  not  produced  by  one  figure,  but  one 
figure  the*  a  through  this  figure,  and  another  through  that,  so 
inquiry  is  to  be  that  clearly  we  must  make  the 4  resolutions  in 
the  same  manner,  but  since  not  every  problem  is 
proved  in  every  5  figure,  but  arranged  in  each,  it  is  evident 
from  the  conclusion  in  what  figure  the  inquiry  must  be 
made.6 

1  Examples  are  not  adduced  to  prove,  but  to  illustrate. 

2  Tanquam  ex  his  ratiocinans.    Averrois. 

5  Ttp  d'  iKTidiaQai  (exhibere  sensui)  ovtoj  xpwfitGa  Ixxsirtp  Kai  r<£  alaQd- 
vtoOai.  Cf.  Aquinas  Opusc.  47.  Zabarella,  cap.  vii.  alaOrjcriQ,  sensa- 
tion, signifies  the  perception  of  the  external  senses.  Vide  Ethics,  b.  vi. 
chap.  2,  and  11  ;  Phys.  b.  iii.  and  vii. 

4  i.  e.  the  several  syllogisms  to  their  proper  figures. 

s  As  no  affirmative  in  the  second  nor  universal  in  the  third. 

*  In  qua  figura  quserendum  sit  problema  aliquod.  Buhle. 


CHAP.  XLI1I.  XLIV.]     THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  167 


Chap.  XLIII. —  Of  Arguments  against  Definition,  simplified. 

With  regard,  however,  to  arguments  against  de-  1  For  brevity-g 

finition,  and  by  which  a  particular  thing  in  the  ?ake  the  thing 

definition   is   attacked,   that  term   must    be  laid  ^definition, 

down  which  is  attacked,  and  not  the  whole  de-  an,d,nojtJe. 

»••/>•  "ii  i  iiiii  whole  defini- 

finition,  for  it  will  result  that  we  shall  be  less   tion  itself,  is  to 
disturbed  by  prolixity,  e.  g.  if  we  are  to  show   be  laid  down- 
that  water   is  humid   potable,  we  must   place   potable  and 
water  as  terms.1 


Chap,  XLIV. — Of  the  Reduction  of  Hypotheticals  and  of  Syllogisms 

ad  impossibile. 

We  must  not  endeavour,  moreover,  to  reduce  hy- 
pothetical syllogisms,  for  we  cannot  reduce  them,    0ur  not  re- 
from  the  things  laid  down,2  since  they  are  not   dheCt£f1gypo~ 
proved  syllogistically,  but  are  all  of  them  admitted 
by  consent.    Thus  if  a  man  supposing  that  except  there  is  one 
certain   power  of  contraries,  there  will  neither  exist  one  sci- 
ence of  them,  it  should  afterwards  be  dialectically  proved 
that  there  is  not  one  *  power  of  contraries ;  for   . 

„  r  tpi  li  iratra.   Waltz. 

instance,  ol  the  wholesome  and  of  the  unwhole- 
some, for  the  same  thing  will  be  wholesome  and  unwholesome 
at  the  same  time — here  it  will  be  shown  that  there  is  not  one 
power  of  all  contraries,  but  that  is  not  a  science,  has  not  been 
shown.  We  must  yet  acknowledge  that  there  is,  not  however 
by  syllogism,  but  by  hypothesis,  wherefore  we  cannot  reduce 
this,  but  that,  we  may,  viz.  that  there  is  not  one  power,  for 
this  perhaps  was  a  syllogism,  but  that  an  hy-  2  Norsyn0. 
pothesis.     The  same  thing  happens  in  the  case  of  gisms  per  im- 

...  i  •   i     •    f  •  possibile. 

syllogisms,  which  inter  a  consequence  per  impos- 
sibile, since  neither  can  we  analyze  these,  though  we  may  a 

1  Waitz  states  that  Pacius  has  misapprehended  this  place,  by  following 
Philoponus,  and  avers  that  SiaXiytaOai  here  is  not  "  disserere  contra 
aliquid,"  sed  "  disputare  de  aliqua  re."  Pacius  thinks  that  the  chapter 
refers  to  such  syllogisms  as  impugn  the  definition. 

2  Ik  twv  KUfiivuiv.  Vide  Whately,  book  ii.  ch.  4  ;  also  Mansel's  Logic, 
Appendix,  note  G.  It  has  been  questioned  whether  hypothetical  can  be 
reduced  to  categorical ;  the  reader  will  find  the  subject  well  and  fully 
treated  in  Mansel,  p.  88. 


168  aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

deduction  to  the  impossible,  (for  it  is  demonstrated  by  syllo- 
gism.) but  the  other  we  cannot,  for  it  is  concluded  from  hy- 
pothesis. They  differ  nevertheless  from  the  before-named,1 
because  we  must  in  them  indeed  have  admitted  some  thing 
previously,  if  we  are  about  to  consent,  as  if,  for  example,  one 
power  of  contraries  should  have  been  shown,  and  that  there 
was  the  same  science  of  them,  now  here  they  admit,  what 
they  had  not  allowed  previously  on  account  of  the  evident 
falsity,  as  if  the  diameter  of  a  square  having  been  admitted 
commensurable  with  the  side,  odd  things  should  be  equal  to 
even. 

Many  others  also  are  concluded  from  hypothe- 

3.  Further  con-       .  ,V  ,      .,     .  .    .  ..  -i     \         i 

sideration  of  sis,  which  it  is  requisite  to  consider,  and  clearly 
hypotheticais      explain ;  what  then  are  the  differences  of  these, 

deterred.  i   •      i 

and  in  how  many  ways  an  hypothetical  syllogism 
is  produced,  we  will  show  hereafter;2  at  present,  let  only  so 
much  be  evident  to  us,  that  we  cannot  resolve  such  syllogisms 
into  figures ;  for  what  reason  we  have  shown. 


Chap.  XLV. — The  Reduction  of  Syllogisms  from  one  Figure 

to  another. 

*  Anal  i.  4  ^-s  many  problems*  as  are  demonstrated  in  many 
and 26 ;  Topics,  figures,  if  they  are  proved  in  one  syllogism,  may 
be  referred3  to  another,  e.  g.  a  negative  in  the 
first  may  be  referred  to  the  second,  and  one  in  the  middle  to 
the  first,  still  not  all,  but  some  only.4  This  will  appear 
l.  Whatever  from  the  following  :  if  A  is  with  no  B,  but  B  with 
syllogisms  are     every  C,  A  is  with  no  C,  thus  the  first  figure 

proved  in  many  .  i      ,    ./>    ,,  x.  -.      ,r 

figures,  may  be   arises;    but  it   the  negative  is   converted,  there 
reduced  from      w[\\  be  the  middle,  for  B  will  be  with  no  A,  and 

one  tiffure  to 

anotner-case of  with  every  C.     In  the  same  manner,  if  the  syllo- 

pTrticuiar  u!d  gism  be  not  universal,  but  particular,  as  if  A  is  with 

the  first  and  no  B,  but  B  is  with  a  certain  C,  for  the  negative 

gures.  kejng  converted  there  will  be  the  middle  figure. 

1  i.  e.  from  syllogisms,  by  hypothesis. 

8  No  work  is  extant  of  Aristotle's  upon  this  subject;  with  St.  Hilaire, 
however,  we  think  that  though  the  subject  is  not  worked  out  by  Aristotle, 
we  have  ample  data  from  which  to  elucidate  it. 

3  avayayilv — vide  Mansel's  Appendix. 

4  i.  e.  may  be  reduced,  or  referred. 


CHAP.  XLV.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  169 

Of  syllogisms,  however,  in  the  middle  figure,  the   2  universal 
universal  will  be  reduced  to  the  first,  but  only  one   in  the  second 
of  the  particular,1  for  let  A  be  with  no  B,  but  with   ""the  first,  but 
every  C,  then  by  conversion  of  the  negative  there   onlv  one  Par_ 
will  be  the  first  figure,  since  B  will  be  with  no  A, 
but  A  with  every  C.     Now  if  the  affirmative  be  added  to  B, 
and  the  negative  to  C,  we  must  take  C  as  the  first  term,  since 
this  is  with  no  A,  but  A  is  with  every  B,  wherefore  C  is  with  no 
B,  neither  will  B  be  with  any  C,  for  the  negative  is  converted. 
If  however  the  syllogism  be  particular,  when  the  negative  is 
added  to  the  major  extreme,  it  will  be  reduced  to  the  first 
figure,  as  if  A  is  with  no  B,  but  with  a  certain  C,  for  by  con- 
version of  the  negative  there  will  be  the  first  figure,  since  B  is 
with  no  A,  but  A  with  a  certain  C.  When  however  the  affirma- 
tive (is  joined  to  the  greater  extreme),  it  will  not  be  resolved, 
as  if  A  is  with  every  B,  but  not  with  every  C,  for  the  proposi- 
tion A  B  does  not  admit  conversion,2  nor  if  it  were  made 
would  there  be  a  syllogism. 

Again,  not  all  in  the  third  figure  will  be  resolv- 
able into  the  first,3  but  all  in  the  first4  will  be  thethirdfigure 
into  the  third,  for  let  A  be  with  every  B,  but  B  with   °,ne  onl>-  when 

,./~i.  ,,  •      -i  «•  ■         •       tne  negative  is 

a  certain  L,  since  then  a  particular  affirmative  is  not  universal, 
convertible,  C  will  be  with  a  certain  B,  but  A  was  ^firs™"*16 
with  every  B,  so  that  there  is  the  third  figure.  Also 
if  the  syllogism  be  negative,  there  will  be  the  same  result,  for 
the  particular  affirmative  is  convertible,  wherefore  A  will  be 
with  no  B,  but  with  a  certain  C.  Of  the  syllogisms  in  the  last 
figure,  one  alone  is  not  resolvable  into  the  first,5  when  the 
negative  is  not  placed  universal,  all  the  rest  however  are  re- 
solved. For  let  A  and  B  be  predicated  of  every  C,  C  there- 
fore is  convertible  partially  to  each  extreme,  wherefore  it  is 
present  with  a  certain  B,  so  that  there  will  be  the  first  figure, 
if  A  is  with  every  C,  but  C  with  a  certain  B.  And  if  A  is 
with  every  C,  but  B  with  a  certain  C,  the  reasoning  is  the  same, 

1  Viz.  Festino  and  not  Baroko.  Of  these  reductions  it  may  be  generally 
observed,  that  only  negative  syllogisms  are  reducible  to  the  second,  and 
only  particular  to  the  third  figure.  Barbara,  Baroko,  and  Bokardo  cannot 
be  ostensively  reduced  to  any  other  figure. 

a  Being  A  it  does  not  admit  simple  conversion. 

3  For  Bokardo  is  excepted. 

4  Darii  and  Ferio — because  universals  cannot  be  reduced  to  the  third 
figure,  in  which  the  conclusion  is  particular.  5  i.  e.  Bokardo. 


17C  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  t. 

for  B  reciprocates  with  C.  But  if  B  is  with  every  C,  and  A  with 
a  certain  C,  B  must  be  taken  as  the  first  term,  for  B  is  with 
every  C,  but  C  with  a  certain  A,  so  that  B  is  with  a  certain  A  ; 
since  however  the  particular  is  convertible,  A  will  also  be  with 
a  certain  B.  If  the  syllogism  be  negative,  when  the  terms 
are  universal,  we  must  assume  in  like  manner,  for  let  B  be  with 
every  C,  but  A  with  no  C,  wherefore  C  will  be  with  a  certain  B, 
but  A  with  no  C,  so  that  C  will  be  the  middle  term.  Likewise, 
if  the  negative  is  universal,  but  the  affirmative  particular,  for 
A  will  be  with  no  C,  but  C  with  a  certain  B  ;  if  however  the 
,  ,  negative  be  taken  as  particular,  there  will  not  be 

a  resolution,*  e.  g.  if  B  is  with  every  C,  but  A  not 
with  a  certain  C,  for  by  conversion  of  the  proposition  B  C, 
both  propositions  will  be  partial. 

4.  The  conver-       It  is  clear  then,  that  in  order  mutually  to  con- 
sum  of  the         Yer^  these  figures,1  the  minor  premise  must  be 

tumor  premise  .    &  * 

necessary  for  converted  in  either  figure,  for  this  being  trans- 
posed a  transition2  is  effected ;  of  syllogisms  in  the 
middle  figure,3  one  is  resolved,4  and  the  other  is  not5  resolved 
into  the  third,  for  when  the  universal  is  negative  there  is  a 
resolution,  for  if  A  is  with  no  B,  but  with  a  certain  C,  both 
similarly  reciprocate  with  A,  wherefore  B  is  with  no  A,  but  C 
with  a  certain  A,  the  middle  then  is  A.  When  however  A  is 
with  every  B,  and  is  not  with  a  certain  C,  there  will  not  be  reso- 
lution, since  neither  proposition  after  conversion  is  universal. 
Syllogisms  also  of  the  third  figure  may  be  resolved  into 
the  middle,  when  the  negative  is  universal,  as  if  A  is  with  no  C, 
but  B  is  with  some  or  with  every  C,  for  C  will  be  with  no  A, 
but  will  be  with  a  certain  B,  but  if  the  negative  be  particular, 
there  will  not  be  a  resolution,  since  a  particular  negative  does 
not  admit  conversion. 

We  see  then  that  the  same  syllogisms6  are  not 
gisms°notSmu°-  resolved  in  these  figures,7  which  were  not  resolved 
tuaiiy  reduci-      into  the  first  figures,  and  that  when  syllogisms 

ble  into  the  °  JO 

other  figures      are  reduced  to  the  first  figure,  these  only  are  con- 
intTtiie^rst0.1     eluded  Per  impossibile. 

How  therefore  we  must  reduce  syllogisms,  and 

1  Viz.  the  first  and  third. 

2  MtrdficHng — transitus  fit  ex  una  in  aliam  figuram. — Buhle. 

3  Those  are  particular,  because  there  is  no  universal  conclusion  in  tho 
third.  4  Festino.  5  Baroko. 

6  Baroko  and  Bokardo.        7  In  the  second  and  third  figures. 


CHAP.  XL VI.]  THE    PRIOR  ANALYTICS.  171 

that  the  figures  are  mutually  resolvable,  appears  from  what 
has  been  said. 

Chap.  XL VI. — Of  the  Quality  and  Signification  of  the  Definite, 
and  Indefinite,  and  Privative. 

There  is  some  difference  in  the  construction  or   i.  Difference  in 
subversion  of  a  problem,  whether  we  suppose  the   ftate™ent  aris- 

,,  ,         ,  .  ,  ,  . r     ,,  ing  from  "not 

expressions  not  to  be  this  particular  thing,  and  to  be "  and  •«  to 
"to  be  not  this  particular  thing,"  have  the  same,  tL^ea'^T^ 
or  different  signification,  e.  g.  "  not  to  be  white,"  (cf-  Herm.  6.) 
and  "  to  be  not  white."  Now  they  do  not  signify  the  same 
thing,  neither  of  the  expression  "  to  be  white,"  is  the  nega- 
tion "to  be  not  white,"  but,  "not  to  be  white;"  and  the 
reason  of  this  is  as  follows.  The  expression  "he  is  able  to 
walk,"  is  similar  to  "  he  is  able  not  to  walk,"  the  expression 
"  it  is  white  "  to,  "  it  is  not  white,"  and  "  he  knows  good,"  to 
"  he  knows  what  is  not  good."  For  these,  "  he  knows  good," 
or  "  he  has  a  knowledge  of  good,"  does  not  at  all  differ,  nei- 
ther "  he  is  able  to  walk,"  and  "  he  has  the  power  of  walk- 
ing ;"  wherefore  also  the  opposites,  "he  is  not  able  to  walk," 
and  "  he  has  not  the  power  of  walking,"  (do  not  differ  from 
each  other).  If  then  "  he  has  not  the  power  of  walking," 
signifies  the  same  as  "he  has  the  power  of  not  walking," 
these  will  be  at  one  and  the  same  time  present  with  the  same, 
for  the  same  person  is  able  to  walk,  and  not  to  walk,  and  is 
cognizant  of  good,  and  of  what  is  not  good,  but  affirmation 
and  negation  being  opposites,  are  not  at  the  same  time  present 
with  the  same  thing.1  Since  therefore  it  is  not  the  same  thing 
"  not  to  know  good,"  and  "  to  know  what  is  not  good,"  nei- 
ther is  it  the  same  thing  to  be  "  not  good "  and  "  not  to  be 
good,"  since  of  things  having  analogy,2  if  the  one  is  different 
the  other  also  differs.  Neither  is  it  the  same  to  be  "  not  equal," 
and  "not  to  be  equal,"3  for  to  the  one,  namely,  "  to  that  which 

1  Aristotle  demonstrates  the  difference  between  infinite  affirmation  and 
finite  negation  by  an  hypothetical  syllogism  leading  to  an  absurdity.  The 
reader  may  find  the  principle  of  proper  logical  affirmation  and  negation 
discussed  in  Whately,  b.  ii.  ch.  2,  and  Hill,  p.  96,  et  seq. 

2  Eandem  rationem. — Buhle.    Similitude  or  identity  of  relation. 

3  For  "to  be  not  equal  "  implies  at  all  events  that  a  thing  exists,  which 
is  affirmation,  but  "not  to  be  equal"  may  be  nothing,  which  is  pure 
negation.     Hence,  as  Taylor  remarks,  Aristotle  infers  that  "  not  every 


172  Aristotle's  organon.  [book   i. 

is  not  equal,"  something  is  subjected,  and  this  is  the  unequal, 
but  to  the  other  there  is  nothing  subjected,  wherefore  "  not 
every  thing  is  equal  or  unequal,"  but  "  every  thing  is  equal 
or  not  equal."  Besides  this  expression,  "  it  is  not  white 
wood,"  and  this,  "  not  is  white  wood,"  are  not  present  toge- 
ther at  the  same  time,  for  if  it  is  "wood  not  white,"  it  will  be 
wood  ;  but  "  what  is  not  white  wood "  is  not  of  necessity 
"wood,"  so  that  it  is  clear  that  of  "it  is  good"  the  negation  is 
not  "it  is  not  good."  If  then  of  every  one  thing  either  the  affirm- 
ation or  negation  is  true,  if  there  is  not  negation,  it  is  evident 
that  there  will  in  some  way  be  affirmation,  but  of  every  affirm- 
ation there  is  negation,  and  hence  of  this  *  the  negation  is,  "it 
is  not  not  good."  They  have  this  order  indeed  with  respect 
2.  order  of  af-  to  eacn  other:  let  to  be  good  be  A,  not  to  be 
rirmation  and  good  B,  to  be  not  good  C  under  B,  not  to  be  not 
good  D  under  A.  With  every  individual  then 
either  A  or  B  will  be  present,  and  (each)  with  nothing  which 
is  the  same  and  C  or  D  with  every  individual,2  and  with 
nothing  which  is  the  same,  and  with  whatever  C  is  present, 
B  must  necessarily  be  present  with  every  individual,  for  if  it 
is  true  to  say  that  "  a  thing  is  not  white,"  it  is  also  true  to  say 
that  "  not  it  is  white,"  for  a  thing  cannot  at  one  and  the  same 
time  be  white  and  not  white,  or  be  wood  not  white  and  be 
white  wood,  so  that  unless  there  is  affirmation,  negation 
will  be  present. — C  however  is  not  always  (consequent)  to  B, 
for  in  short,  what  is  not  wood  will  not  be  white  wood,  on  the 
contrary,  with  whatever  A  is  present  D  also  is  present  with 
„  c  every  individual,  for  either  C  or  D  will  be  pre- 

sent. As  however  "to  be  not  white"*  and  "to 
be  white,"  f  cannot  possibly  co-subsist,  D  will  be 
present,  for  of  what  is  white  we  may  truly  say,  that  it  is  not  not 
white,  yet  A  is  not  predicated  of  every  D,  for,  in  short,  we  can- 
not truly  predicate  A  of  what  is  not  wood,  namely,  to  assert 
that  it  is  white  wood,  so  that  D  will  be  true,  and  A  will  not 
be  true,  namely,  that  it  is  white  wood.  It  appears  also,  that 
A  and  C  are  present  with  nothing  identical,  though  B  and  D 
may  be  present  with  the  same. 

thing"  is  equal  or  unequal,  because  that  which  is  not  is  neither  equai 
nor  unequal ;  but  that  "  every  thing  "  is  equal  or  is  not  equal,"  because 
this  is  contradiction. 

1  "  It  is  not  good  :  " — affirmative.       2  Taylor  omits  this  clause. 


CHAP.  XL VI.] 


THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS. 


173 


Privatives  also  subsist  similarly  to  this  position    „  _  , 

.  ,  .,  i   /•       i  ii»  3-  Relation  be- 

with  respect  to  attributes,1  lor  let  equal  be  A,  not  tween  (&  aT„- 
equal  B,  unequal  C,  not  unequal  D.  In  many  ^Tind'attri- 
things  also,  with  some  of  which  the  same  thing  is  butes  (kut^o- 
present  and  not  with  others,  the  negative  may  be  p 
similarly  true,  that,  "  not  all  things  are  white,"  or  "  that  not 
each  thing  is  white  ;  "  but,  "  that  each  thing  is  not  white,"  or, 
"  that  all  things  are  not  white,"  is  false.  So  also  of  this 
affirmation,  "  every  animal  is  white,"  the  negation  is  not, 
"every  animal  is  not  white,"  for  both  are  false,  but  this, 
"  not  every  animal  is  white."  Since  however  it  is  clear  that 
"  is  not  white,"  signifies  something  different  from  "  not  is 
white,"  and  that  one  is  affirmation  and  the  other  negation,  it 
is  also  clear  that  there  is  not  the  same  mode  of  demonstrating 
each,  for  example,2  "  whatever  is  an  animal  is  not  white,"  or 
"  happens  not  to  be  white ;"  and  that  we  may  truly  say,  "it 
is  not  white,"  for  this  is  "  to  be  not  white."  Still  there  is 
the  same  mode  as  to  it  is  true  to  say  it  is  white  or  not  white, 
for  both  are  demonstrated  constructively*  through  *  KaTa<TKeVaa- 
the  first  figure,  since  the  word  "true"  is  similarly   T«*ac,  "con- 

...     n  structivc, 

arranged  with  "  is,"  for  of  the  assertion  "  it  is  Averr. "  con- 
true  to  say  it  is  white,"  the  negation  is  not,  "  it  is  Buhk'^' 
true  to  say  it  is  not  white,"  but  "  it  is  not  true  to  '    T»e  differ- 
say   it   is   white."      But    if  it    is    true    to    say, 
"whatever  is  a  man  is  a3  musician,  or  is  not4  a 
musician,"  we  must  assume  that  "  whatever  is  an  in"the"mo<ie  oi 
animal  is  either  a  musician  or  is  not  a  musician,"5  demonstratIon 
and  it  Avill  be  demonstrated,  but  that  "  whatever  +  v***™™- 

..,,.,  ,      ,     TiKus,  "de- 

ls a  man  is  not  a  musician,    is  shown  negatively  J   structure." 

according  to  the  three  modes6  stated.  Averrois. 

In  short,  when  A  and  B  are  so,  as  that  they  5.  Relative 

cannot  be  simultaneously  in  the  same  thing,  but  provt-d^n'cer- 

one  of  them  is  necessarily  present  to  every  indi-  tain  eases- 


enceof  the  cha- 
racter of  asser- 
tion shown  by 
the  difference 


1  Karriyopiai— predicamenta.  Averrois.  The  word  must  here  be  under- 
stood as  opposed  to  privation  in  the  sense  of  "  habits,"  not  as  a  species 
of  quality,  as  it  is  considered  in  the  Categor.  eh.  8. 

'*  We  cannot  demonstrate  the  two  assertions  given,  in  the  same  way. 

3  An  universal  tiniie  affirmative. 

*  An  universal  indefinite  affirmative. 

5  This  is  the   major  premise,  to  which  if  the  minor, 
animal,"  is  added,  the  syllogism  will  be  in  Barbara. 

'  Viz.  Celarent,  Cesare,  Camestres. 


every  man  is  an 


174  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

vidual,  and  again  C  and  D  likewise,  lut  A  follows  C 
and  does  not  reciprocate,  D  will  also  follow  B,  and  will  not 
reciprocate,  and  A  and  D  may  be  with  the  same  thing,  but  B 
and  C  cannot.  In  the  first  place  then,  it  appears  from  this 
that  D  is  consequent  to  B,  for  since  one  of  C  D  is  necessarily 
present  with  every  individual,  but  with  what  B  is  present  C 
cannot  be,  because  it  introduces  with  itself  A,  but  A  and  B 
cannot  consist  with  the  same,  D  is  evidently  a  consequent. 
Again,  since  C  does  not  reciprocate  with  A,  but  C  or  D  is 
present  with  every,  it  happens  that  A  and  D  will  be  with  the 
same  thing,  but  B  and  C  cannot,  because  A  is  consequent  to 

C,  for  an  impossibility  results,1  wherefore  it  appears  plain 
that  neither  does  B  reciprocate  with  D,  because  it  would  hap- 
pen that  A  is  present  together  with  D.2 

6.  Fallacy  Sometimes  also  it  occurs  that  we  are  deceived 

arising  from       Dy  sucn  an  arrangement  of  terms,  because  of  our 

not  assuming  J  .o  .  „       ,  . 

opposites  pro-  not  taking  opposites  rightly,  one  of  which  must 
perly-  necessarily  be  with  every  individual,  as  if  A  and  B 

cannot  be  simultaneously  with  the  same,  but  it  is  necessary  that 
the  one  should  be  with  what  the  other  is  not,  and  again  C  and  D 
in  like  manner,  but  A  is  consequent  to  every  C  ;  for  B  will  hap- 
pen necessarily  to  be  with  that  with  which  D  is,  which  is  false. 
For  let  the  negative  of  A  B  which  is  F  be  assumed,  and  again 
the  negative  of  C  D,  and  let  it  be  H,  it  is  necessary  then,  that 
either  A  or  F  should  be  with  every  individual,  since  either  af- 
firmation or  negation  must  be  present.  Again  also,  either  C 
or  H,  for  they  are  affirmation  and  negation,  and  A  is  by  hy- 
pothesis present  with  every  thing  with  which  C  is,  so  that  H 
will  also  be  present  with  whatever  F  is.  Again,  since  of  F  B, 
one  is  with  every  individual,  and  so  also  one  of  H  D,  and  H 
is  consequent  to  F,  B  will  also  be  consequent  to  D,  for  this 
we  know.     If  then  A  is  consequent  to  C,  B  will  also  follow 

D,  but  this  is  false,  since  the  sequence  was  the  reverse  in 
things  so  subsisting,  for  it  is  not  perhaps  necessary  that  either 
A  or  F  should  be  with  every  individual,  neither  F  nor  B,  for  F 
is  not  the  negative  of  A,  since  of  "  good"  the  negation  is  "  not 
good,"  and  "  it  is  not  good"  is  not  the  same  with  "  it  is  neither 
good  nor  not  good."  It  is  the  same  also  of  C  D,  for  the  as- 
sumed negatives  are  two. 

'  i.  e.  A  and  B  would  co-subsist. 

2  Because  A  cannot  be  present  with  B. 


CHAP.  I.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  175 


BOOK  II , 


Chap.  I. — Recapitulation. — Of  the  Conclusions  of  certain 

Syllogisms. 

In  how  many  figures,  through  what   kind  and   i.  Reference  to 
number  of  propositions,  also  when  and  how  a  syl-   observations, 
logism  is  produced,  we  have  therefore  now  ex-   Universal  syl- 

,°.  r  ,  .       ,        ,  logisms  infer 

plained ;    moreover,  what  points   both  the   con-   many  conciu- 
structor   and    subverter   of    a   syllogism    should   slons' 
regard,  as  well  as  how  we  should  investigate  a  proposed  sub- 
ject after  every  method ;  further,  in  what  manner  we  should 
assume  the  principles  of  each  question.     Since,   2.  so  also  do 
however,    some    syllogisms    are    universal,    but   particular  af- 

'  ii-ii  •  formative,  but 

others  particular,  all  the  universal  always  con-  not  the  nega- 
clude  a  greater  number  of  things,  yet  of  the  par-  tive  Particular- 
ticular,  those  which  are  affirmative  many  things,  but  the 
negative  one  conclusion  only.  For  other  propositions  are  con- 
verted, but  the  negative  is  not  converted,  but  the  conclusion 
is  something  of  somewhat ;  hence  other  syllogisms  conclude  a 
majority  of  things,  for  example,  if  A  is  shown  to  be  with  every 
or  with  a  certain  B,  B  must  also  necessarily  be  with  a  certain  A, 
and  if  A  is  shown  to  be  with  no  B,  B  will  also  be  with  no  A,  and 
this  is  different  from  the  former.  If  however  A  is  not  with  a  cer- 
tain B,  B  need  not  be  not  present  with  a  certain  A,  for  it  possibly 
may  be  with  every  A.1     This  then  is  the  common    „  ^.„ 

>  ii  •  i  i  ^-  D'flerence 

cause  or  all  syllogisms,  both  universal  and  par-   between  uni- 
ticular  ;    we   may  however  speak  differently   of  fir^and'tiiose 
universals,  for  as  to  whatever  things  are  under   ofthesesond 
the  middle,  or  under  the  conclusion,  of  all  there 
will  be  the  same  syllogism,  if  some  are  placed  in  the  middle, 
but  others  in  the  conclusion,2  as,  if  A  B  is  a  conclusion  through 
C,  it  is  necessary  that  A  should  be  predicated  of  whatever  is 

1  As  if  A  -were  "  man  ; "  a  "  certain  animal,"  a  certain  B  ;  and  animal, 
B ;  therefore  though  "  man"  is  not  present  with  "  a  certain  animal,"  (e.  g. 
"a  lion,")  yet  "animal  "  is  with  every  "man." 

2  Hence  three  conclusions,  he  means,  may  be  drawn  from  the  same 
syllogism,  one  of  the  minor  extreme,  another  of  what  is  under  the  minor 
and  the  third  of  what  is  the  subject  of  the  middle. 


176  Aristotle's  obganon.  [book  ii. 

under  B  or  C,  for  if  D  is  in  the  whole  of  B,  but  B  in  the 
whole  of  A,  D  will  also  be  in  the  whole  of  A.  Again,  if  E  is 
in  the  whole  of  C,  and  C  is  in  A,  E  will  also  be  in  the  whole 
of  A,  and  in  like  manner  if  the  syllogism  be  negative  ;  but  in 
the  second  figure  it  will  be  only  possible  to  form  a  syllogism 
of  that  which  is  under  the  conclusion.  As,  if  A  is  with  no  B, 
but  is  with  every  C,  the  conclusion  will  be  that  B  is  with  no  C  ;  if 
therefore  D  is  under  C,  it  is  clear  that  B  is  not  with  it,  but  that 
it  is  not  with  things  under  A,  does  not  appear  by  the  syllogism, 
though  it  will  not  be  with  E,  if  it  is  under  A.  But  it  has 
been  shown  by  the  syllogism  that  B  is  with  no  C,  but  it  was  as- 
sumed without  demonstration1  that  it  is  not  with  A,  wherefore 
n  does  not  result  by  the  syllogisms  that  B  is  not  with  E. 
Nevertheless  in  particular  syllogisms  of  things  under  the  con- 
clusion, there  is  no  necessity  incident,  for  a  syllogism  is  not 
•  ^P6ra<r^.)      Produced,2  when  this*  is  assumed  as  particular, 

JT4re  'n  Ist  but  there  wil1  be  of>  a11  tIlings  under  the  middle, 
yet  not  by  that  syllogism,  e.  g.  if  A  is  with  every  B, 
but  B  with  a  certain  C,  there  will  be  no  syllogism  of  what  is 
placed  under  C,  but  there  will  be  of  what  is  under  B,  yet  not 
through  the  antecedent  syllogism.  Similarly  also  in  the  case 
of  the  other  figures,  for  there  will  be  no  conclusion  of  what  is 
under  the  conclusion,  but  there  will  be  of  the  other,  yet  not 
through  that  syllogism  ;  in  the  same  manner,  as  in  universals, 
from  an  undemonstrated  proposition,  things  under  the  middle 
were  shown,  wherefore  either  there  will  not  be  a  conclusion 
there,3  or  there  will  be  in  these  also.4 

Chap.  II. — On  a  true  Conclusion  deduced  from  false  Premises  in  the 

first  Figure. 

tnuhlrfeLuy  It  is  tnerefore  possible  that  the  propositions  may 

of  propositions,  be  true,  through  which  a  syllogism  arises,  also 

byThV^ncfu-  that  tne7  may  be  false>  also  that  one  may  be  true 

sion.  and  the  other  false ;  but  the  conclusion  must  of 

1  A  being  assumed  of  no  B,  B  is  in  a  manner  assumed  of  no  A,  be- 
cause a  proposition  universal  negative  reciprocates. 

a  Because  in  the  2nd  figure  both  propositions  affirm  ;  hence  nothing  is 
concluded. 

3  In  universal  syllogisms. 

4  In  particular.  For  the  recognition  of  the  indirect  modes,  in  this 
chapter,  by  Aristotle,  see  Mans?!,  p.  66,  and  74,  note. 


CHAP.  II.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  177 

necessity  be  either  true  or  false.    From  true  propositions  then 
we  cannot  infer  a  falsity,  but  from  false  premises 

we  may  infer  the  truth,  except  that  not  the  why*  *T""»non°X* 

but  the  mere  that  (is  inferred),  since  there  is  not  propter  quid 

a  syllogism  of  the  why  from  false  premises,  and  Averr.  (kill's 

for  what  reason  shall  be  told  hereafter.1  Logic'  p-  287-> 

First  then,  that  we  cannot  infer  the  false  from 

true  premises,  appears  from  this :  if  when  A  is,  it  fn^h^ue 

is  necessary  that  B  should  be,  when  B  is  not  it  from  false  pre- 

is  necessary  that  A  is  not,  if  therefore  A  is  true,  thefeW^rom 

B  is  necessarily  true,  or  the  same  thing:  (A)  would  *rue  Prt;m;s,es- 

J  a  •  Prool — (Vide 

at  one  and  the  same  time  be  and  not  be,2  which   Aidrich.genera! 
is  impossible.     Neither  must  it  be  thought,  be-    ^l^?tsyll°' 
cause  one  term,  A,  is  taken,  that  from  one  certain 
thing  existing,  it  will  happen  that  something  will  result  from 
necessity,  since  this  is  not  possible,  for  what  results 
from  necessity  is  the  conclusion,  and  the  fewest 
things  through  which  this  arises  are  three  terms,  but  two  in- 
tervals and  propositions.  If  then  it  is  true  that  with  whatever 
B  is  A  also  is,  and  that  with  whatever C  is  B  is,  it  is  necessary 
that  with  whatever  C  is  A  also  is,  and  this  cannot  be  false,  for 
else  the  same  thing  would  exist  and  not  exist  at  the  same  time. 
Wherefore  A  is  laid  down  as  one  thing,  the  two 
propositions  being  co-assumed.     It  is  the  same 
also  in  negatives,  for  we  cannot  show  the  false  from  what  are 
true  ;  but  from  false  propositions  we  may  collect  the  truth,3 
either  when  both  premises  are  false,  or  one  only,  and  this  not 
indifferently,  but  the  minor,  if  it  comprehend  the  whole  false,4 
but  if  the  whole  is  not  assumed  to  be  false,  the 
true  may  be  collected  from  either.f   Now  let  A  be   sumed  fell?, 
with  the  whole  of  C,  but  with  no  B,  nor  B  with  C, 

1  In  ch.  2  of  1st  book,  Post  Anal. 

-  Because  it  is  true  by  hypothesis,  but  B  being  denied  true,  A  cannot 
be  true. 

3  See  the  general  rules  of  syllogism  in  Aldrich,  and  Hill's  Logic. 
Hereafter  Aristotle  expounds  this  more  fully ;  he  means  that  a  true  con- 
clusion may  always  be  inferred  in  the  first  figure,  unless  the  major  is 
wholly  false,  and  the  minor  true. 

*  By  this  expression  he  means,  as  he  explains  further  on,  an  universal 
proposition,  contrary  to  the  true,  as  "  no  man  is  an  animal."  An  universal 
contradictory  to  the  true  is  of  course  a  particular  false  proposition,  (vide 
table  of  opposition, )  and  a  proposition  is  said  to  be  false  in  part,  when 
what  is  partly  true  and  partly  false,  is  affirmed,  or  denied,  universally. 

w 


178  aristotle's  organon.  [book  ii. 

and  this  may  happen  to  be  the  case,  as  ankaal  is  with  no  stone, 

nor  stone  present  with  any  man,  if  then  A  is  assumed  present 

with  every  B,  and  B  with  every  C,  A  will  be  with  every  C, 

so  that  from  propositions  both  false,  the  conclusion 

*  Example  (1.)         ...  ,  r  .  L  .  •        1  * 

will  be  true,  since  every  man  is  an  animal.* 
So  also  a  negative  conclusion  (is  attained),  for  neither  A 
may  be  assumed,  nor  B  present  with  any  C,  but 
let  A  be  with  every  B,  for  example,  as  if,  the  same 
terms  being  taken,  man  was  placed  in  the  middle,  for  neither 
animal  nor  man  is  with  any  stone,  but  animal  is 

4    Man  * 

X  Aniniai.         with  every  man.    Wherefore  if  with  whatf  it  jis 
,    v  present  universally,  it  is  assumed  to  be  present  with 

§  In  the  major.     1  J\  .  5 

none,§  but  with  what  it  is  not  present,  we  assume 
II  in  the  minor.    t^at  -j.   -g  present  -with   every  individual, ||  from 

s  Example  (2.)   both  these  false  premises,  there  will  be  a  true  con  • 
4  clusion.^f    The  same  may  be  shown  if  each  pre- 

mise is  assumed  partly  false,  but  if  only  one  is 
admitted  false,  if  the  major  is  wholly  false,  as  A  B,  there  will 
not  be  a  true  conclusion,  but  if  B  C,  (the  minor  is  wholly 
3.  instance  of  false,)  there  will  be  (a  true  conclusion).  Now  I 
afaise propo-  mean  by  a  proposition  wholly  false  that  which  is 
contrary  (to  the  true),  as  if  that  was  assumed  pre- 
sent with  every,  which  is  present  with  none,  or  that  present 
with  none,  which  is  present  with  every.  For  let  A  be  with 
no  B,  but  B  with  every  C,  if  then  we  take  the  proposition  B 

Ex.  1.  Every  stone  is  an  animal  B                 A 

Every  man  is  a  stone  Ex.  3.  Every  animai  is  a  stone 

Every  man  is  an  animal.  C                   B 

Ex.  2.  No  man  is  an  animal  Every  man  is  an  animal 

Every  stone  is  a  man  C              A 

.  • .     No  stone  is  an  animal.  . " .     Every  man  is  a  stone. 

B  A 

Ex.  4.  Every  thing  white  is  an  animal 
C  B 

Every  swan  is  white 
C  A 

.  • .    Every  swan  is  an  animal. 

B  A 

Ex.  5.  Nothing  white  is  an  animal 
C  B 

All  snow  is  white 
C  A 

. " .  No  snow  is  an  animal. 


chap,  n.] 


THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS. 


179 


*  Example  (3.) 


5. 


C  as  true,  but  the  whole  of  A  B  as  false,  and  that  A  is  with 
every  B,  it  is  impossible  for  the  conclusion  to  be  true,  for  it 
was  present  with  no  C,  since  A  was  present  with  none 
of  what  B  was  present  with,  but  B  was  with 
every  C* 

In  like  manner  also  the  conclusion  will  be  false, 
if  A  is  with  every  B,  and  B  with  every  C,  and 
the  proposition  B  C  is  assumed  true,  but  A  B  wholly  false, 
and  that  A  is  present  with  no  individual  with  which  B  is,  for 
A  will  be  with  every  C,  since  with  whatever  B  is,  A  also  is, 
but  B  is  with  every  C.  It  is  clear  then,  that,  the 
major  premise  beingassumed  wholly  false,  whether 
it  be  affirmative  or  negative,  but  the  other  pre- 
mise being  true,  there  is  not  a  true  conclusion  ; 
if  however  the  whole  is  not  assumed  false,  there 
will  be.  For  if  A  is  with  every  C,  but  with  a  cer- 
tain B,  and  B  is  with  every  C  ;  e.  g.  animal  with 
every  swan,  but  with  a  certain  whiteness,  and  w  like- 
ness with  every  swan,  if  A  is  assumed  present  with  every  B, 
and  B  with  every  C,  A  will  also  be  truly  present 
with  every  C,  since  every  swan  is  an  animal,  "j" 

So  also  if  A  B  be  negative,  for  A  concurs  with 
a  certain  B,  but  with  no  C,  and  B  with  every  C, 
as  animal  with  something  white,  but  with  no 
whiteness  with  all  snow  ;  if  then  A  is  assumed  present 
with  no  B,  but  B  with  every  C,  A  will  be  present  t  Example  (5 ) 
with  no  C.  ~\. 

If  however  the  proposition  A  B  were  assumed   5  If  the  major 
wholly  true,  but  B  C  wholly  false,  there  will  be  a   is  true  wholly, 

.  11       •  l  ,i  •  *    n  i     •  but  the  minor 

true  syllogism,1  as  nothing  prevents  A  irom  being    wholly  false, 
with  every  B  and  every  C,  and  yet  B  with  no  C,  as   ^conclusion 
is  the  case  with  species  of  the  same  genus,  which 


4.  When  the 
major  is  wholly 
false,  but  the 
minor  is  true, 
the  conclusion 
is  false  ;  but 
when  the  whole 
is  not  false,  the 
conclusion  is 
true. 
Affirmative. 


t  Example  (4.) 
2.  Negative. 

snow,   and 


1  Here  is  another  instance  of  "  syllogism  "  being  employed  in  its  pure 
sense,  equivalent  to  "  conclusion,"  frequently  it  signifies  the  propositional 
arrangement  necessarily  inferring  the  conclusion. 


B  A 

Ex.  6.  Every  horse  is  an  animal 
C  B 

Every  man  is  a  horse 
C  A 

.  '.    Every  man  is  an  animal. 


B  A 

Ex.  7.  No  music  is  an  animal 
C  '  B 

All  medicine  is  music 
C  A 

.  •  .  No  medicine  is  an  animal. 


N  2 


180  aristotle's  organon.  [book  ii. 

are  not  subaltern,  for  animal  concurs  both  with  horse  and 
man.  but  horse  with  no  man  ;  if  therefore  A  is  assumed  pre- 
1   Affirmative.   sent  w^n  eveiT  B,  and  B  with  every  C,  the  con- 
clusion will  be  true,  though  the  whole  proposition 
B  C  is  false.*    It  will  be  the  same,  if  the  propo- 
sition A  B  is  negative.     For  it  will  happen  that  A  will  be 
neither  with  any  B,  nor  with  any  C,  and  that  B  is  with  no  C, 
as  genus  to  those  species  which  are  from  another  genus,  for 
animal  neither  concurs  with  music  nor  with  medicine,  nor 
music  with  medicine :  if  then  A  is  assumed  present  with  no 
j      .    B,  but  B  with  every  C,  the  conclusion  will  be 
true.f    Now  if  the  proposition  B  C  is  not  wholly 
but  partially  false,  even  thus  the  conclusion  will  be  true.    For 
nothing  prevents  A  from  concurring  with  the  whole  of  B, 
and  the  whole  of  C,  and  B  with  a  certain  C,  as  genus  with 
species  and  difference,  thus  animal  is  with  every  man  and 
with  every  pedestrian,  but  man  concurs  with  something,  and 
not  with  every  thing  pedestrian  :  if  then  A  is  assumed  pre- 
,  „        .  ,„ ,   sent  with  every  B,  and  B  with  every  C,  A  will 
also  be  present  with  every  u,|  which  will  be  true. 

B  A 

Ex.  8.  Every  man  is  an  animal 

C  B 

Every  pedestrian  thing  is  a  man 
B  A 

.  • .  Every  pedestrian  thing  is  an  animal. 

B  A 

Ex.  9.  No  prudence  is  an  animal 

C  B 

All  contemplative  knowledge  is  prudence 
C  A 

.  • .  No  contemplative  knowledge  is  an  animal. 

B  A 

Ex.  10.  All  snow  is  an  animal 
C  B 

Something  white  is  snow 
C  A 

.  • .  Something  white  is  an  animal. 

B  A 

Ex.  11>  No  man  is  an  animal 

C  B 

Something  white  is  a  man 

C  A 

.  • ,  Something  white  is  not  an  animal. 


CHAP.  II.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  181 

The  same  will  occur  if  the  proposition  A  B  be  2  Negaive 
negative.  For  A  may  happen  to  be  neither  with 
any  B,  nor  with  any  C,  yet  B  with  a  certain  C,  as  genus  with 
the  species  and  difference  which  are  from  another  genus. 
Thus  animal  is  neither  present  with  any  prudence  nor  with 
any  thing  contemplative,  but  prudence  is  with  something 
contemplative  ;  if  then  A  is  assumed  present  with  no  B,  but 
B  with  every  C,  A  will  be  with  no  C,  which  will  .  Example(9  } 
be  true.* 

In   particular  syllogisms  however,   when  the 
whole  of  the  major  premise  is  false,  but  the  other   lars  with  ama. 
true,  the  conclusion  may  be  true  ;  also  when  the  ^^y^"1  a 
major  A  B  is  partly  false,  but  B  C  (the  minor)   there  may  he 
wholly  true  ;  and  when  A  B  the  major  is  true,   ^rnue  conclu' 
but  the  particular  false,  also  when  both  are  false. 
For  there  is  nothing  to  prevent  A  from  concurring  with  no 
B,  but  with  a  certain  C,  and  also  to  prevent  B  from  being 
present  with  a  certain  C,  as  animal  is  with  no    }   Affirmative. 
snow,  but  is  with  something  white,  and  snow  with 
something  white.     If  then  snow  is  taken  as  the  middle,  and 
animal  as  the  first  term,  and  if  A  is  assumed  present  with  the 
whole  of  B,  but  B  with  a  certain  C,  the  whole  proposition 
A  B  will  be  false,  but  B  C  true,  also  the  conclu-  f  Examp]e(10 } 
sion  will  be  true.j 

It  will  happen  also  the  same,  if  the  proposition  A  B  is  ne- 
gative, since  A  may  possibly  be  with  the  whole  of  B,  and  not 
with  a  certain  C,  but  B  may  be  with  a  certain  C.  2  Neg8tive 
Thus  animal  is  with  every  man,  but  is  not  conse- 
quent to  something  white,  but  man  is  present  with  something 
white  ;  hence  if  man  be  placed  as  the  middle  term,  and  A  is 
assumed  present  with  no  B,  but  B  with  a  certain  C,  the  con- 
clusion will  be  true,  though  the  whole  proposition  ^  Example(11>) 
A  B  is  false.! 

If  again  the  proposition  A  B  be  partly  false,1    7.  if  the  major 

1  Taylor  and  Buhle  insert,  "  when  B  C  is  true,"  which  is  omitted  by 
Waitz  and  Averrois. 

B  A 

Ex.  12.  Every  thing  beautiful  is  an  animal 
C  B 

Something  great  is  beautiful 
C  A 

.  • .  Something  great  is  an  animal. 


182  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  n. 

is  partly  false,    the  conclusion  will  be  true.     For  nothing  hinders 
the  conclusion    j±  from  concurring  with  B,  and  with  a  certain  C, 

will  be  true.  ,  t»   p  ,     .      °     .  ,  •      r-i        i  , 

and  Jb  troni  being  with  a  certain  b  ;  thus  animal 
may  be  with  something  beautiful,  and  with  something  great,1 
,    ._      ..       and  beauty  also  may  be  with  something  great.    If 

1.  Affirmative.  .     .   J  J  °  to 

then  A  is  taken  as  present  with  every  B,  and  B 

with  a  certain  C,  the  proposition  A  B  will  be  partly  false ; 

but  B  C  will  be  true,  and  the  conclusion  will 

*  Example  (12.)    .  o, 

be  true.* 

2.  Negative.  Likewise  if  the  proposition  A  B  is  negative, 

for  there  will  be  the  same  terms,  and  placed  in 
the  same  manner  for  demonstration. f 
minor~JfariseUe'  Again,  if  A  B  be  true,  but  B  C  false,  the 
conclusion  will  be  true,  since  nothing  prevents  A 
from  being  with  the  whole  of  B,  and  with  a  certain  C,  and  B 
from  being  with  no  C.  Thus  animal  is  with  every  swan,  and 
with  something  black,  but  a  swan  with  nothing  black  ;  hence, 
if  A  is  assumed  present  with  every  B,  and  B  with  a  cer- 
+  _        :  ... .  tain  C,  the  conclusion  will  be  true,  though  B  C 

t  Example  (14.)    .  '  'to 

is  false. J 

B  A 

Ex.  13.  Nothing  beautiful  is  an  animal 
C  B 

Something  great  is  beautiful 

C  A 

.  • .   Something  great  is  not  an  animal. 
1  i.  e.  to  prove  a  true  conclusion  from  premises,  one  partly  false,  and 
the  other  true. 

B  A 

Ex.  14.  Every  swan  is  an  animal 
C  B 

Something  black  is  a  swan 
C  A 

. '  .  Something  black  is  an  animal. 
B  A 

Ex.  15.  No  number  is  an  animal 
C  B 

Something  white  is  number 

C  A 

. ' .  Something  white  is  not  an  animal. 
B  A 

Ex.  16.  Every  thing  white  is  an  animal 
C  B 

Something  black  is  white 
B  A 

. ' .  Something  black  is  an  animal. 


CHAP.  II.]  THE   PRIOR   AXALYTICS.  183 

Likewise  if  the  proposition  A  B  be  taken  as  4.  Maju:  nega- 
negative,  for  A  may  be  with  no  B,  and  may  not  be  tive" 
with  a  certain  C,  yet  B  may  be  with  no  C.  Thus  genus  may 
be  present  with  species,  which  belongs  to  another  genus,  and 
with  an  accident,  to  its  own  species,  for  animal  indeed  concurs 
with  no  number,  and  is  with  something  white,  but  number  is 
with  nothing  white.  If  then  number  be  placed  as  the  mid- 
dle, and  A  is  assumed  present  with  no  B,  but  B  with  a 
certain  C,  A  will  not  be  with  a  certain  C,  which  would  be 
true,  and  the  proposition  A  B  is  true,  but  B  C 

n  1        #  *  Example  (15.) 

Also  if  A  B  is  partly  false,  and  the  proposition  minorwhoiiyV 
B  C  is  also  false,  the  conclusion  will  be  true,  for  false- 
nothing  prevents  A  from  being  present  with  a  certain  B,  and 
also  a  certain  C,  but  B  with  no  C,  as  if  B  should  be  contrary 
to  C,  and  both  accidents  of  the  same  genus,  for  animal  is  with 
a  certain  white  thing,  and  with  a  certain  black  thing,  but 
white  is  with  nothing  black.  If  then  A  is  assumed  present 
with  every  B,  and  B  with  a  certain  C,  the  con- 

.       .  .Ju   ,  '  ,  t  Example  (16.) 

elusion  will  be  true.j 

Likewise  if  the  proposition  A  B  is  taken  nega-    6  Ne  ative 
tively,  for  there  are  the  same  terms,  and  they  will 
be  similarly  placed  for  demonstration. J '  t  Example  (1 7.) 

If  also  both  are  false,  the  conclusion  will  be   7  Both  false 
true,  since  A  may  be  with  no  B,  but  yet  with  a 

1  To  prove  a  true  conclusion  may  be  drawn  from  false  premises. 

B  A 

Ex.  17.   Nothing  white  is  an  animal 
C  B 

Something  black  is  white 

C  A 

.  • .  Something  black  is  not  an  animal. 
B  A 

I5x.  IS.  Every  number  is  an  animal 
C  B 

Something  white  is  number 
C  A 

•  .  Something  white  is  an  animal. 

B  A 

Ex    19.  No  swan  is  an  animal 

C  B 

Something  black  is  a  swan 

C  A 

.  • .  Something  black  is  not  an  arums!. 


184  ARISTOTLE'S    ORGANON.  [BOOK   II. 

certain  C,  but  B  with  no  C,  as  genus  with  species  of  another 
genus,  and  with  an  accident  of  its  own  species,  for  animal  is 
with  no  number,  but  with  something  white,  and  number  with 
nothing  white.  If  then  A  is  assumed  present  with  every  B, 
and  B  with  a  certain  C,  the  conclusion  indeed  will 

*  Example  (18.)    .  ,  ..      ,       ,       .  .  .,,„„,.« 

be  true,  while  both  the  premises  will  be  false.* 
tiveIaJ°r  "ega"  Likewise  if  A  B  is  negative,  for  nothing  pre- 
vents A  from  being  with  the  whole  of  B,  and 
from  not  being  with  a  certain  C,  and  B  from  being  with  no 
C,  thus  animal  is  with  every  swan,  but  is  not  with  something 
black,  swan  however  is  with  nothing  black.  Wherefore,  if 
A  is  assumed  present  with  no  B,  but  B  with  a  certain  C,  A 
.„        .  ,.„,  is  not  with  a  certain  C,  and  the  conclusion  will 

t  Example  (19.)    ,  .  ,  .     ' 

be  true,  but  the  premises  false.y1 

Chap.  Ill — The  same  in  the  middle  Figure. 

i   in  this  In  tlie  middle  figure  it  is  altogether  possible  to 

figure  we  ma;  infer  truth  from  false  premises,  whether  both  are 
fromSmisTs,  ass"med  wholly  false,  or  one  partly,  or  one  true, 
either  one  or  but  the  other  wholly  false,  whichever  of  them  is 
partian/false'    place(l  false,  or  whether  both  are  partly  false,  or 

one  is  simply  true,  but  the  other  partly  false,  or 
one  is  whclly  false,  but  the  other  partly  true,  and  as  well  in 
i.  universais.    universal  as  in  particular  syllogisms.      For  if  A 

is  with  noB  but  with  every  C,  as  animal  is  with  no 
stone  but  with  every  horse,  if  the  propositions  are  placed  con- 
trariwise, and  A  is  assumed  present  with  every  B,  but  with 

no  C,  from  premises  wholly  false,  the  conclusion 

xampie  (i.)    w^\  be  true  j  Likewise  if  A  is  with  every  B  but 

§  Example  (2.)   with  no  C,  for  the  syllogism  will  be  the  same.§  * 

1  Vide  Waitz,  vol.  i.  pp.  483  and  487. 

B  A  B  A 

Ex.  1.  Every  stone  is  an  animal  Ex.  2.  No  horse  is  an  animal 
C                   A  C  A 

No  horse  is  an  animal  Every  stone  is  an  animal 

C  B  C  B 

.  • .  No  horse  is  a  stone.  .  ■ .  No  stone  is  a  horse. 

2  One  of  these  syllogisms  is  in  Cesare,  but  the  other  in  Camestres  : 
yet  both  are  similar  in  respect  of  being  produced  by  the  same  terms ; 
proving  the  truth  from  false  premises,  and  deducing  almost  the  same 
conclusion. 


CnAP.    Ill/  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  185 

Again,  if  the  one  is  wholly  false,  but  the  other   2  0ne  whol]y 
wholly  true,  since  nothing  prevents  A  from  being   false,  the  other 
with  every  B  and  with  every  C,  but  B  with  no  C, 
as    genus    with    species    not    subaltern,  for    animal    is    with 
every  horse   and  with   every  man,  and  no  man  is   a  horse. 
If   then  it  is   assumed  to  be   with  every  individual   of  the 
one,  but  with   none  of  the  other,  the  one  proposition  will 
be  wholly  false,  but  the  other  wholly  true,  and  the  conclu- 
sion  will  be   true   to  whichever  proposition  the    *  Example  (3.) 
negative  is  added.1*     Also  if  the  one  is  partly   3  one  partly 
false,  but  the  other  wholly  true,  for  A  may  possibly   false- 
be  with  a  certain  B  and  with  every  C,  but  B  with  no  C,  as  ani- 
mal is  with  something  white,  but  with  every  crow,  and  white- 
ness with  no  crow.  If  then  A  is  assumed  to  be  present  with  no 
B,  but  with  the  whole  of  C,  the  proposition  A  B  will  be  partly 
false,  but  A  C  wholly  true,  and  the  conclusion   t  Example  (4.) 
will  be  true,  f     Likewise  when  the  negative  is   4.  Minor  or 
transposed,2  since  the    demonstration  is   by  the   negative. 

1  i.  e.  whether  the  major  or  minor  premise  is  negative. 

B  A  B  A 

Ex.  3.  Every  horse  is  an  animal  No  horse  is  an  animal 

C  A  C  A 

No  man  is  an  animal  Every  man  is  an  animal 

C  B  C  B 

.  • .  No  man  is  a  horse.  . ' .  No  man  is  a  horse. 

B  A 

Ex.  4.  Nothing  white  is  an  animal 
C  A 

Every  crow  is  an  animal 
C  B 

.  '  .  No  crow  is  white. 

*  If  the  minor  premise  denies. 

B  A  B  A 

Ex.  5.  Every  crow  is  an  animal  Ex.  6.  Every  thing  white  is  an  animal 
C                   A  C  A 

Nothing  white  is  an  animal  No  pitch  is  an  animal 

C  B  C  B 

.  • .  Nothing  white  is  a  crow.  .  ■ .  No  pitch  is  white. 

B  A 

Ex.  7.  Every  thing  white  is  an  animal 
C  A 

Nothing  black  is  an  animal 
C  B 

.  • .  Nothing  black  is  white. 


186  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  ii. 

•  Example  (5).   same  terms.*     Also  if  the  affirmative  premise  is 

5.  Affirmative    partly  false,  but  the  negative  wholly  true,  for  no- 

thing prevents  A  being  present  with  a  certain  B,  but 
not  present  with  the  whole  of  C,  and  B  being  present  with  no  C, 
as  animal  is  with  something  white,  but  with  no  pitch,  and 
whiteness  with  no  pitch.  Hence  if  A  is  assumed  present  with 
the  whole  of  B,  but  with  no  C,  A  B  is  partly  false,  but  A  C 
t  Example  (6.)   wholly  true,  also  the   conclusion  will   be   true.f 

6.  Eoth  partly    Also  if  both  propositions  are  partly  false,  the  con- 

clusion will  be  true,  since  A  may  concur  with  a  cer- 

B  A 

Ex.  8.  Nothing  white  is  can  animal 
C  A 

Every  thing  black  is  an  animal 
C  B 

.  • .  Nothing  black  is  white. 

B  A 

Ex.  9.  No  man  is  an  animal 

C  A 

Something  white  is  an  animal 
C  B 

.  * .  Something  white  is  not  a  man. 

B  A 

Ex.  10.  Every  thing  inanimate  is  an  animal 
C  A 

Something  white  is  not  an  animal 
C  B 

. " .  Something  white  is  not  inanimate. 
B  A 

Ex.  11.  No  number  is  an  animal 

C  A 

Something  inanimate  is  an  animal 
C  B 

.  * .  Something  inanimate  is  not  number. 
B  A 

Ex.  12.  Every  man  is  an  animal 

C  A 

Something  pedestrian  is  not  an  animal 
C  B 

.  • .  Something  pedestrian  is  not  a  man. 

B  A 

Ex.  13.  Every  science  is  an  animal 
C  A 

A  certain  man  is  not  an  animal 
C  B 

•  • .  A  certain  man  is  not  science 


CHAP.  III.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  187 

tain  B,  and  with  a  certain  C,  but  B  with  no  C,  as  animal  may  be 
with  something  white,  and  with  something  black,  but  white- 
ness with  nothing  black.  If  then  A  is  assumed  present  with 
every  B,  but  with  no  C,  both  premises  are  partly 
false,  but  the  conclusion  will  be  true.*  Likewise  *  ExamPle(7-) 
when  the  negative  istransposedbythesameterms.f    t  Example  (8.) 

This  is  evident  also  as  to  particular  syllogisms, 
since  nothing  hinders  A  from  being  with  every 

B,  but  with  a  certain  C,  and  B  from  not  being  with  a  certain 

C,  as  animal  is  with  every  man,  and  with  something  white, 
yet  man  may  not  concur  with  something  white.  If  then  A  is 
assumed  present  with  no  B,  but  with  a  certain  C,  1.  Major  nega- 
the  universal  premise  will  be  wholly  false,  but  the  tive' 
particular  true,  and  the  conclusion  true.}  Like-  *  Example (9.) 
wise  if  the  proposition  A  B  is  taken  affirmative,  affirmative 
for  A  may  be  with  no  B,  and  may  not  be  with  a 

certain   C,§   and  B  not   present  with   a  certain   omitted  by 
C ;   thus  animal  is  with  nothing  inanimate,  but   Ta>'lor- 
with  something  white,  and  the  inanimate  will  not  be  present 
with  something  white.     If  then  A  is  assumed  present  with 
every  B,  but  not  present  with  a  certain  C,  the  universal  pre- 
mise A  B  will  be  wholly  false,  but  A  C  true,  and  the  con- 
clusion true. ||     Also  if  the  universal  be  taken  true,   y  Example  (io.) 
but  the  particular  false,  since  nothing  prevents  A   3.  Univ.  true, 
from  being  neither  consequent  to  any  B   nor  to   par 
any  C,  and  B  from  not  being  with  a  certain  C,  as  animal  is 
consequent  to  no  number,  and  to  nothing  inanimate,  and  num- 
ber is  not  consequent  to  a  certain  inanimate  thing.     If  then  A 
is  assumed  present  with  no  B,  but  with  a  certain  C,  the  con- 
clusion will  be  true,  also  the  universal  proposition,  but  the 
particular  will  be  false.^f     Likewise  if  the  uni-         am 
versal  proposition  be  taken  affirmatively,  since  A 
may  be  with  the  whole  of  B  and  with  the  whole 
of  C,  yet  B  not  be  consequent  to  a  certain  C,  as  genus  to  species 
and  difference,  for  animal  is  consequent  to  every  man,  and  to 
the  whole  of  what  is  pedestrian,  but  man  is  not  (consequent) 
to  every  pedestrian.     Hence  if  A  is  assumed  present  with 
the  whole  of  B,  but  not  with  a  certain  C,  the  universal  pro- 
position will  be  true,  but  the  particular  false,  and     _        ,    , , 

,  ,      .  l  •  Example;  12., 

the  conclusion  true. 


188  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  ii. 

Moreover  it  is  evident  that  from  premises  both 
5.  case  of  both  fajge  there  will  be  a  true  conclusion,  if  A  happens 
to  be  present  with  the  whole  of  B  and  of  C,  but 
B  to  be  not  consequent  to  a  certain  C,  for  if  A  is  assumed 
present  with  no  B,  but  with  a  certain  C,  both  propositions 
are  false,  but  the  conclusion  will  be  true.     In  like  manner 
when  the  universal  premise  is  affirmative,  but  the  particular 
negative,  since  A  may  follow  no  B,  but  every  C,  and  B  may 
not  be  present  with  a  certain  C,  as  animal  is  consequent  to 
no  science,  but  to  every  man,  but  science  to  no  man.     If  then 
A  is  assumed  present  with  the  whole  of  B,  and  not  conse- 
quent to  a  certain  C,  the  premises  will  be  false, 
xam  but  the  conclusion  will  be  true.* 

Chap.  IV. — Similar  Observations  upon  a  true  Conclusion  from  false 
Premises  in  the  third  Figure. 

There  will  also  be  a  conclusion  from  false  pre- 
gameaTwith  mises  in  the  last  figure,  as  well  when  both  are 
the  preceding     fa]se  an(j  either  partly  false  or  one  wholly  true, 

tiffurcs.  ■  *  wf  * 

but  the  other  false,  or  when  one  is  partly  false, 
and  the  other  wholly  true,  or  vice  versa,  in  fact  in  as  many 
ways  as  it  is  possible  to  change  the  propositions.  For  there 
is  nothing  to  prevent  either  A  or  B  being  present  with  any  C, 
l.  Both  univ.  but  yet  A  may  be  with  a  certain  B  ;  *  thus  neither 
affirm.  man,  nor  pedestrian,  is  consequent  to  any  thing  in- 

1  Taylor  has  made  a  mistake  here  both  in  the  letters  and  in  this 
and  the  succeeding  syllogistic  example.  I  have  followed  Waitz,  Buhle, 
Averrois,  and  Bekker;  for  the  general  rules  to  which  these  chapters 
refer,  the  reader  may  find  the  subject  fully  treated  in  Whately  and  Hill. 

C  A 

Ex.  1.  Every  thing  inanimate  is  a  man. 
C  B 

Every  thing  inanimate  is  pedestrian 
B  A 

. ' .  Something  pedestrian  is  a  man. 
C  A 

Ex.  2.  No  swan  is  an  animal 
C  B 

Every  swan  is  black 

B  A 

.  * .  Something  black  is  not  an  animal. 


CHAP.  IV.]  THE   PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  189 

animate,  yet  man  consists  with  something  pedestrian.    If  then 
A  and  B  are  assumed  present  with  every  C,  the  propositions 
indeed  will  be  wholly  false,  but  the  conclusion   *  Example  (i.) 
true.*     Likewise  also  if  one  premise  is  negative,   2.  onenega- 
but  the  other  affirmative,  for  B  possibly  is  present   tive 
with  no  C  but  A  with  every  C,  and  A  may  not  be  with  a  certain 

B.  Thus  blackness  consists  with  no  swan,  but  animal  with  every 
swan,  and  animal  is  not  present  with  every  thing  black. 
Hence,  if  B  is  assumed  present  with  every  C,  but  A  with  no 

C,  A  will  not  be  present  with  a  certain  B,  and  the  conclusion 
will  be  true,  but  the  premises  false. f     If,  how-    t  Example  (2.) 
ever,  each  is  partly  false,  there  will  be  a  true  con-   3.  One  partly 
elusion,  for  nothing  prevents  A  and  B  being  pre-  false' 

sent  with  a  certain  C,  and  A  with  a  certain  B,  as  whiteness 
and  beauty  are  consistent  with  a  certain  animal,  and  white- 
ness is  with  something  beautiful,  if  then  it  is  laid  down  that 
A  and  B  are  with  every  C,  the  premises  will  indeed  be  partly 
false,  but  the  conclusion  true.J  Likewise  if  A  C  j  Example  (3.) 
is  taken  as  negative,  for  nothing  prevents  A  not 
consisting  with  a  certain  C,  but  B  consisting  with  *■  Nesative»- 

C  A 

Ex.  3.  Every  animal  is  white 
C  B 

Every  animal  is  beautiful 
B  A 

.  * .  Something  beautiful  is  white. 

C  A 

Ex.  4.  No  animal  is  white 
G  B 

No  animal  is  beautiful 

B  A 

. ' .  Something  beautiful  is  not  white. 

C  A 

Ex.  5.  No  swan  is  an  animal 
C  B 

Every  swan  is  white 

B  A 

.  • .  Something  white  is  not  an  animaL 

C  A 

Ex.  6.  No  swan  is  black 

C  B 

Every  swan  is  inanimate 

B  A 

. ' .  Something  inanimate  is  not  black. 


190  amstotle's  org  anon.  [book  n. 

a  certain  C,  and  A  not  consisting  with  every  B  as  whiteness 
is  not  present  with  a  certain  animal,  but  beauty  is  with  some 
one,  and  whiteness  is  not  with  every  thing  beautiful,  so  that 
if  A  is  assumed  present  with  no  C,  but  B  with  every  C,  both 
premises  will  be  partly  false,  but  the  conclusion  will  be 
»  Example  (4.)  true-*  Likewise,  if  one  premise  be  assumed 
5.  one  wholly  wholly  false,  but  the  other  wholly  true,  for  both 
false,  the  other   A  and  B  may  follow  every  C,  but  A  not  be  with 

a  certain  B,  as  animal  and  whiteness  follow  every 
swan,  yet  animal  is  not  with  every  thing  white.  These  terms 
therefore  being  laid  down,  if  B  be  assumed  present  with  the 
whole  of  C,  but  A  not  with  the  whole  of  it,  B  C  will  be  wholly 

true,  and  A  C  wholly  false,  and  the  conclusion  will 

t  Example  (5.)     be  ^  j    g()  ^  .f  fi  Q  .g  ^  ^  A  Q  ^^  ^ 

6-  there  are  the  same  terms  for  demonstration,  black, 

t  Example  (6.)   swan,  inanimate.1  J     Also  even  if  both  premises 
r.  Both  affirm.    are  assumed  affirmative,  since  nothing  prevents 
B  following  every  C,  but  A  not  wholly  being  pre- 
sent with  it,  also  A  may  be  with  a  certain  B,  as  animal  is 

1  i.  e.  to  deduce  a  true  conclusion  from  false  premises. 
C  A 

Ex.  7.  Every  swan  is  black 
C  B 

Every  swan  is  an  animal 
B  A 

. " .  Some  animal  is  black. 

C  A 

Ex.  8.  Every  swan  is  an  animal 
C  B 

Every  swan  is  black 

B  A 

.  • .  Something  black  is  an  animal. 
C  A 

Ex.  9.  Every  man  is  beautiful 
C  B 

Every  man  is  a  biped 
B  A 

.  • .  Some  biped  is  beautiful. 

C  A 

Ex.  10.  Every  man  is  a  biped 
C  B 

Every  man  is  beautiful 

B  a 

Something  beautiful  is  a  biped. 


CHAP.  IV.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  191 

with  every  swan,  black  with  no  swan,  and  black  with  a  cer- 
tain animal.  Hence  if  A  and  B  are  assumed  present  with 
every  C,  B  C  will  be  wbolly  true,  but  A  C  wholly  false,  and 
the  conclusion  will  be  true.*  Similarly,  again,  if  .  Example  c ) 
A  C  is  assumed  true,  for  the  demonstration  will 
be  through  the  same  terms.j  Again,  if  one  is  f  ExamPIe  (»•) 
wholly  true,  but  the  other  partly  false,  since  B  may  be  with 
every  C,  but  A  with  a  certain  C,  also  A  with  a  certain  B,  as 
biped  is  with  every  man,  but  beauty  not  with  every  man,  and 
beauty  with  a  certain  biped.  If  then  A  and  B  are  assumed 
present  with  the  whole  of  C,  the  proposition  B  C  is  wholly 
true,  but  A  C  partly  false,  the  conclusion  will  also  be 
true.|  Likewise,  if  A  C  is  assumed  true,  and  B  j  Example  (9.) 
C  partly  false,  for  by  transposition  of  the  same  8. 
terms,1  there  will  be  a  demonstration^  Again,  if  §Exampie(io.) 
one  is  negative  and  the  other  affirmative,  for  since  B  may 
possibly  be  with  the  whole  of  C,  but  A  with  a  certain  C,  when 
the  terms  are  thus,  A  will  not  be  with  every  B.  If  B  is  as- 
sumed present  with  the  whole  of  C,  but  A  with  none,  the 
negative  is  partly  false,  but  the  other  wholly  true,  the  con- 
clusion will  also  be  true.  Moreover,  since  it  has  been  shown 
that  A  being  present  with  no  0,  but  B  with  a  certain  C,  it  is 
possible  that  A  may  not  be  with  a  certain  B,  it  is  clear  that 
when  A  C  is  wholly  true,  but  B  C  partly  false, 
the  conclusion  may  be  true,  for  if  A  is  assumed 
present  with  no  C,  but  B  with  every  C,  A  C  is  wholly  true, 
but  B  C  partly  false. 

Nevertheless,  it  appears  that  there  will  be  alto- 
gether a  true  conclusion  by  false  premises,  in  the   foUowt^same 
case  also  of  particular  syllogisms.     For  the  same   TXi}e'  '•  e- those 

,  ,  ii  •  with  one  uni- 

terms  must  be  taken,  as  when  the  premises  were  versa]  and  one 
universal,  namely,  in  affirmative  propositions,  af-  n^SeCUlarpre" 
Urinative  terms,  but  in  negative  propositions,  nega- 
tive terms,  for  there  is  no  difference2  whether  when  a  thing 
consists  with  no  individual,  we  assume  it  present  with  every,3 
or  being  present  with  a  certain  one,  we  assume  it  present  uni- 

1  In  these  two  last  examples,  the  greater  and  less  extremes  change 
places,  yet  a  true  conclusion  is  deduced. 

3  i.  e.  things  assumed  in  particular,  do  not  differ  from  the  same  things 
assumed  in  universal  syllogisms. 

1  i.  e.  entirely  false. 


192  aristotle's  organox.  [book  11. 

„    ,,  versally,1  as  far  as  regards  the  setting  out  of  the 

3.  Alsonega-  J '  °  .  °   . 

thes.  terms  \l  the  like  also  happens  in  negatives.      We 

ciuswnlsT'lse  see  tnen  tnat  ^  tne  conclusion  is  false,  those  things 

there  must  be  from  which  the  reasoning  proceeds,  must  either 

or  inoreDof  the  all  or  some  of  them  be  false ;  but  when  it  (the 

premises— but  conclusion)   is   true,   that   there  is   no   necessity, 

this  does  not  '  '.  .  .      J 

hold  good  vice  either  that  a  certain  thing,  or  that  all  things, 
ofthta.ReaS°n  should  be  true;  but  that  it  is  possible,  when 
nothing  in  the  syllogism  is  true,  the  conclusion 
should,  nevertheless,  be  true,  yet  not  of  necessity.  The 
reason  of  this  however  is,  that  when  two  things3  so  sub- 
sist with  relation  to  each  other,  that  the  existence  of  the  one 
necessarily  follows  from  that  of  the  other,  if  the  one4  does  not 
exist,  neither  will  the  other  be,5  but  if  it6  exists  that  it  is  not 
necessary  that  the  other7  should  be.  If  however  the  same 
thing8  exists,  and  does  not  exist,  it  is  impossible  that  there 
should  of  necessity  be  the  same  (consequent);9  I  mean,  as  if 
A  being  white,  B  should  necessarily  be  great,  and  A  not  be- 
ing white,  that  B  is  necessarily  great,  for  when  this  thing  A 
being  white,  it  is  necessary  that  this  thing  B  should  be  great, 
but  B  being  great,  C  is  not  white,  if  A  is  white,  it  is  neces- 
sary that  C  should  not  be  white.  Also  when  there  are  two 
things,10  if  one  is,11  the  other 12  must  necessarily  be,  but  this  not 

1  i.  e.  partly  false. 

2  That  is,  the  terms  being  proposed,  it  may  be  shown,  that  we  can  de- 
duce a  true  inference  from  false  premises. 

3  i.  e.  antecedent  and  consequent. 
*  The  consequent. 

5  The  antecedent.  It  is  valid  to  argue  from  the  subversion  of  the  con- 
sequent, the  subversion  of  the  antecedent ;  thus  if  man  is,  animal  is,  but 
animal  is  not,  therefore  man  is  not. 

6  The  consequent. 

7  The  antecedent.  It  is  not  necessary  that  this  should  exist,  because 
an  inference  of  the  existence  of  the  antecedent  from  that  of  the  conse- 
quent is  invalid. 

8  The  antecedent. 

9  Because  we  cannot  collect  the  consequent  from  the  affirmation  or 
negation  of  the  antecedent;  as,  if  man  is,  animal  is;  and  if  man  is  not, 
animal  is. 

10  That  is,  two  subject  terms,  as  A  and  B.  He  now  enunciates  that  an 
argument  from  the  negative  of  the  consequent  to  the  negative  of  the  ante- 
cedent is  valid.  Buhle  and  Waitz  read  this  passage  differently  to  Taylor, 
by  the  insertion  of  the  letter  merely. 

11  That  is,  the  antecedent.  ,2  The  consequent. 


CHAP.  V.j  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  193 

existing,  it  is  necessary  that  A*  should  not  be,   „  (Illud , 
thus  B  not  being  great,  it  is  impossible  that  A   Buhie.  i.  e.the 
should  be  white. 

But  if*  when  A  is  not  white,  it  is  necessary  that  B  should 
be  great,  it  will  necessarily  happen  that  B  not  being  great,  B 
itself  is  great,  which  is  impossible.  For  if  B  is  not  great,  A 
will  not  be  necessarily  white,  and  if  A  not  being  white,  B 
should    be    great,    it   results,    as    through    three 

r*  \    *i     Z-CTl-  4.  \     •<■  ■  *  +  t  Example  (11.; 

(terms),  that  it  B  is  not  great,  it  is  great. j 

Chap.  V. — Of  Demonstration  in  a  Circle,  in  the  first  Figure.1 

The  demonstration  of  things  in  a  circle,  and  from  _  . . 
each  other,  is  by  the  conclusion,  and  by  taking  this  kind  of  de- 
one  proposition  converse  in  predication,  to  con-  "^^'X- 
elude  the  other,  which  Ave  had  taken  in  a  former 
syllogism.  As  if  it  were  recpiired  to  show  that  A  is  with  every 
0,  we  should  have  proved  it  through  B  ;2  again,3  if  a  person 
should  show  that  A  is  with  B,  assuming  A  present  with  C, 
but  C  with  B,  and  A  with  B  ;  first,  on  the  contrary,  he  as- 
sumed B  present  with  C.  Or  if  it  is  necessary  to  demonstrate 
that  B  is  with  C,4  if  he  should  have  taken  A  (as  predicated ) 
of  C,  which  was  the  conclusion,5  but  B  to  be  present  with  A, 
for  it  was  first  assumed6  conversely,  that  A  was  with  B.  It 
is  not  however  possible  in  any  other  manner  to  demonstrale 
them  from  each  other,  for  whether  another  middle7  is  taken, 
there  will  not  be  (a  demonstration)  in  a  circle,  since  nothing 
is  assumed  of  the  same,8  or  whether  something  of  these  (is  as- 
sumed), it  is  necessai-y  that  one  alone9  should  (be  taken),  for 

Ex.  11.  If  A  is  not  white  B  is  great 

If  B  is  not  great  A  is  not  white 
.  ' .   If  B  is  not  great  it  is  great. 

1  Vide  Mansel's  Logic,  on  this  kind  of  demonstration,  pp.  103 — 105 
8  The  first  syllogism,  ABC. 

3  The  second,  A  C  B,  in  which  the  major  of  the  first  proposition  is 
proved. 

4  i.  e.  the  minor  proposition  of  the  first  syllogism. 

*  In  the  first  syllogism.  6  In  the  first  syllogism. 
7  i.  e.  different  from  ABC,  the  original  terms. 

s  Of  the  premises  in  the  former  syllogism. 

*  Of  the  premises  of  the  first  syllogism. 

D 


194  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  n 

if  botli l  there  will  be  the  same  conclusion,  when 
stratioiTcrfthis  we  need  another.  In  those  terms  then  which  are 
kind  not  tmiy    not  converted,  a  syllogism  is  produced  from  one 

made,  except  -  -,•'.,.  n  x  .-, 

through  con-  undemonstrated  proposition,  tor  we  cannot  demon- 
and1henlbyS'  strate  by  this  term,  that  the  third  is  with  the  mid- 
assumption  die,  or  the  middle  with  the  first,  but  in  those  which 
cesso,'C'°oniy.  are  converted  we  may  demonstrate  all  by  each 
other,  as  if  A  B  and  C  reciprocate ;  for  A  C  can 
be  demonstrated  by  the  middle,2  B  ;  again,3  A  B  (the  major) 
through  the  conclusion,  and  through  the  proposition  B  C,  (the 
minor)  being  converted  ;  likewise 4  also  B  C  the  minor  through 
the  conclusion,  and  the  proposition  A  B  con- 
ofthee2nd  verted.  We  must  however  demonstrate  the  pro- 
syiiogism.  position  C  B,*  and  B  A,f  for  we  use  these  alone 
tVJet'hsilo-01,  undemonstrated,  if  then  B  is  taken  as  present 
gism.  with  every  C,J  and  C  with  every   A,  there  will 

tThesthsyiio-  De  a  syllogism  of  B  in  respect  to  A.§  Again,  if 
§  i.e.  that  Bis  C  is  assumed  present  with  every  A,  and  A  with 
with  a.  every  B,|]  it  is  necessary  that  C  should  be  present 

giIm?CA Is"0"  with  eveiT  B.  in  both5  syllogisms  indeed,  the  pro- 
position  C  A  is  taken  undemonstrated,  for  the 
others  were  demonstrated.     Wherefore  if  we    should  show 
this,  they  will  all  have  been  shown  by  each  other, 
gfcmf cb  aU°    I*" then  C  is  assumed  present  with  every  B,^[  and 
B  with  every  A,  both  propositions  are  taken  de- 
monstrated, and  C  is  necessarily  present  with  A,  hence  it  is 
clear  that  in  convertible  propositions  alone,  demonstrations 
may  be  formed  in  a  circle,  and  through  each  other,  but  in 
others  as  we  have  said  before,6  it  occurs  also  in  these 7  that 

1  Premises  in  the  first  syllogism 

2  The  first  syllogism  of  a  circle,  ABC. 

3  The  second  syllogism,  ACB.  4   The  sixth  syllogism,  B  A  C. 

5  i.  e.  in  the  fifth  and  third. 

6  One  proposition  is  not  demonstrated  in  a  circle. 

7  i.  e.  in  the  3rd,  4th,  and  5th,  in  which  the  converse  propositions  are 
proved.  It  must  be  remembered  that  a  circle  consists  of  six  syllogisms, 
the  others  flowing  from  the  first :  of  these,  the  2nd  proves  the  major, 
and  the  6th  the  minor  of  the  first,  but  both  assume  the  conclusion  of  the 
first,  to  which  the  2nd  adds  the  converse  minor,  and  the  6th  the  con- 
verse major  of  the  first :  hence  the  2nd  and  6th  prove  directly  the  pro- 
positions of  the  first,  but  assume  two  converse  propositions,  which  have 
also  to  be  proved  to  make  the  circle  complete.    This  is  done  by  the  third 


CHAP.  V.]  THE    PRIOR  ANALYTICS.  19o 

we  use  the  same  thing  demonstrated  for  the  pur-  *  The  major  of 

pose  of  a  demonstration.     For  C  is  demonstrated  *l \he  minor  of 

of  B,*  and  B  of  A,f  assuming  C  to  be  predicated  4th. 

of  A,  J  but  C  is  demonstrated  of  A  §  by  these  pro-  3rd.  e  major 

positions, II  so  that  we  use  the  conclusion '  for  de-  •>  J,nJ fhelt^>- 

1  V1  II  C  B  and  B 

monstration.  a. 

In  negative  syllogisms  a  demonstration  through 
each  other  is  produced  thus :  let  B  be  with  every   negatives! 
C,  but  A  present  with  no  B,  the  conclusion  that 
A  is  with  no  C.     If  then  it  is  again   necessary  to  conclude 
that  A  is  with  no  B,  which  we  took  before,  A  will  be  with  no 
C,  but  C  with  every  B,  for  thus  the  proposition  becomes  con- 
verted.    But  if  it  is  necessary  to  conclude  that  B  is  with  C, 
the  proposition  A  B  must  no  longer  be  similarly  . 

converted,  tor  it  is  the  same  proposition, i  that  B 
is  with  no  A,  and  that  A  is  with  no  B,  but  we  must  assume 
that  B  is  present  with  every  one  of  which  A  is  present  with 
none.  Let  A  be  present  with  no  C,  which  was  the  con- 
clusion, but  let  B2  be  assumed  present  with  every  of 
which  A  is  present  with  none,  therefore  B  must  necessarily 
be  present  with  every  C,  so  that  each  of  the  assertions  which 
are  three  becomes  a  conclusion,  and  this  is  to  demonstrate  in 
a  circle,  namely,  assuming  the  conclusion  and  one  premise 
converse  to  infer  the  other.3     Now  in  particular    .   T 

.  ,  .     r  4.  In  particu- 

syllogisms  we  cannot  demonstrate  universal  pro-   lars  the  major 
position  through  others,  but  we  can  the  particular,    stratedlbut  the 
and  that  we  cannot  demonstrate  universal  is  evi-   minor  is. 
dent,  for  the  universal  is  shown  by  universals,    . 
but  the  conclusion  is  not  universal,  and  we  must 
demonstrate  from  the  conclusion,  and  from  the  other  proposi- 
tion.    Besides,  there  is  no  syllogism  produced  at  all  when  the 
proposition  is  converted,  since  both  premises  become  particular. 

and  fifth  syllogisms,  the  major  of  the  3rd  and  the  minor  of  the  5th  being 
identical,  as  well  as  the  latter  being  the  converse  conclusion  of  the  first, 
proved  by  the  4th.  Thus  a  circle  may  be  divided  into  two  parts,  of 
which  the  conclusion  of  the  1st,  2nd,  and  6th  are  direct,  but  those  of 
the  3rd,  4th,  and  5th  are  converse. 

1  Of  the  4th,  i.  e.  in  order  to  prove  the  propositions  of  the  same  fourth. 

2  Omitted  by  Taylor.  3  Vide  Whately  and  Hill. 

Ex.  1.   Every  B  is  A 
Some  C  is  B 
.  •  .    Some  G  is  A. 
o  2 


196  aristoxle's  organon.  [book  ii. 

But  we  can  demonstrate  a  particular  proposition,  for  let  A  be 
2  demonstrated  of  a  certain  C  through  B,  if  then 

B  is  taken  as  present  with  every  A,  and  the  con- 
clusion remains,  B  will  be  present  with  a  certain  C,  for  the 
,  „  ,    first  figure  is  produced,  and  A  will  be  the  middle.* 

*  Example  (1.)  ■=  V„    .  '        .  . 

JNevertheless  it  the  syllogism  is  negative,  we  can- 
not demonstrate  the  universal  proposition  for  the  reason  ad- 
duced before,  but  a  particular  one  cannot  be  demonstrated,  if 
A  B  is  similarly  converted  as  in  universals,  but  we  may  show 
it  by  assumption,1  as  that  A  is  not  present  with  something, 
but  that  B  is,  since  otherwise  there  is  no  syllogism  from  the 
particular  proposition  being  negative. 

Chap.  VI. —  Of  the  same  in  the  second  Figure. 

In  the  second  figure  we  cannot  prove  the  affirm- 

1.   In  uni-  ..         .       .,  .  t      -.  , 

versais  of  the  ative  in  this  mode,  but  we  may  the  negative  ;  the 
.second  figure      affirmative  therefore  is  not  demonstrated,  because 

an  affirmative        .  .  .  ' 

proposition  is  there  are  not  both  propositions  affirmative,  for 
"trated?011"        the  conclusion  is  negative,  but  the  affirmative  is 

demonstrated  from  propositions  both  affirmative, 
the  negative  however  is  thus  demonstrated.  Let  A  be  with 
every  B,  but  with  no  C,  the  conclusion  B  is  with  no  C,  if  then  B 
is  assumed  present  with  every  A,  it  is  necessary  that  A  should 
be  present  with  no  C,  for  there  is  the  second  figure,  the 
middle  is  B.     But  if  A  B  be  taken  negative,  and  the  other 

proposition  affirmative,  there  will  be  the  first 
I'atfvUeYshe  ne~    figure,  for  C  is  present  with  every  A,  but  B  with 

no  C,  wherefore  neither  is  B  present  with  any 
A,  nor  A  with  B,  through  the  conclusion  then  and  one  pro- 
position a  syllogism  is  not  produced,  but  when  another  pro- 
position is  assumed  there  will  be  a  syllogism.  But  if  the 
3.  in  partieu-  syllogism  is  not  universal,  the  universal  proposi- 
lars  the  parti-     tion2  is  not  demonstrated  for  the  reason  we  have 

(.mar  proposi-  .  _  „ 

tion  alone  is       given  before,"*  but  the  particular4  is  demonstrated 

1  That  is,  hypothetically.  As  regards  the  concluding  sentence  of  this 
chapter,  1  have  followed  Bekker,  Buhle,  and  Taylor,  in  preference  toWaitz 
and  Averrois,  since  though  I  favour  the  grammatical  construction  of  the  tw; 
latter,  the  sense  of  the  context  is  against  them.  2  The  major. 

3  Because  the  conclusion  being  assumed,  and  the  minor  of  Festino  or 
Baroko,  both  propositions  are  particular,  hence  there  is  no  conclusioo. 

4  The  minor. 


CUAP.  VII.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  197 

when  the  universal  is  affirmative.     For  let  A  be    demonstrated 
with  every  B,  but  not  with  every  C,  the  conclu-   versaiisaffirm- 
sion  that  B  is  not  with  a  certain  C,  if  then  B  is   ative- 
assumed  present  with  every  A,  but  not  with  every  C,  A  will 
not  be  with  a  certain  C,  the  middle  is  B.     But  if  the  universal 
is  negative,  the  proposition  A  C  will  not  be  de-   2 
monstrated,  A  B  being  converted,  for  it  will  hap- 
pen either  that  both 1  or  that  one2  proposition  will  be  negative; 
so  that  there  will  not  be  a  syllogism.     Still  in  the  same  man- 
ner there  will  be  a  demonstration,  as  in  the  case  of  universals, 
if  A  is  assumed  present  with  a  certain  one,  with  which  B  is 
not  present. 

Chap.  VII. —  Of  the  same  in  the  third  Figure. 

In  the  third  figure,  when  both  propositions  are   L  In  this 
assumed  universal,  we  cannot  demonstrate  reci-   figure,  when 

.  i-i  ii  i  •       Dotn  proposi- 

procally,  for  the  universal  is  shown  through  uni-   tions  are  uni- 
versals, but  the  conclusion  in  this  figure  is  always   JJ^SSto! 
particular,  so  that  it  is  clear  that  in  short  we  can-   tion  in  a  circle. 
not  demonstrate  an  universal  proposition  by  this   2^  There  wm 
figure.     Still  if  one  be  universal  and  the  other   tion  where  the 
particular,  there  will  be  at  one  time  and  not  at  JJ**"  jj™j;e 
another  (a  reciprocal  demonstration)  ;  when  then   major  particu- 
both  propositions  are  taken  affirmative,  and  the 
universal  belongs  to  the  less  extreme,  there  will  be,  but  when 
to  the  other,3  there  will  not  be.    For  let  A  be  with 
every  C,  but  B  with  a  certain  (C),  the  conclusion 
A  B,  if  then  C  is  assumed  present  with  every  A,  C  has  been 
shown  to  be  with  a  certain  B,  but  B  has  not  been  shown  to  be 
with  a  certain  C.    But  it  is  necessary  if  C  is  with  a  certain  B, 
that  B  should  be  with  a  certain  C,  but  it  is  not  the  same  thing, 
for  this  to  be  with  that,  and  that  with  this,  but  it  must  be  as- 
sumed that  if  this  is  present  with  a  certain  that,  that  also  is 
with  a  certain  this,  and  from  this  assumption  there  is  no  longer 
a  syllogism  from  the  conclusion  and  the  other  proposition.     If 

1  If  the  conclusion  is  assumed  and  the  major  premise. 

2  If  a  negative  conclusion  is  assumed,  with  a  minor  affirmative. 

3  When  the  major  is  universal  and  the  minor  particular  there  will  not 
be  a  trae  circle,  because  from  the  conclusion  and  the  major  premise  the 
minor  is  not  proved. 


198  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  it. 

however  B  is  with  every  C,  but  A  with  a  certain 
C,  it  will  be  possible  to  demonstrate  A  C,  when  C 
is  assumed  present  with  every  B,  but  A  with  a  certain  (B). 
For  if  C  is  with  every  B,  but  A  with  a  certain  B,  A  must 
necessarily  be  with  a  certain  C,  the  middle  is  B.  And  when 
one  is  affirmative,  but  the  other  negative,  and  the 
affirmatives  affirmative  universal,  the1  other  will  be  demon- 
universal  there  strated ;  for  let  B  be  with  every  C,  but  A  not  be 
uoneo"°therpar-  with  a  certain  (C),  the  conclusion  is,  that  A  is  not 
ticuiar  nega-      vvith  a  certain  B.     If  then  C  be  assumed  besides 

tive.  .  ,  _       .  -ii 

present  with  every  B,  A  must  necessarily  not  be 
.4.  Not  when      vv^itli  a  certain  C,  the  middle  is  B.    But  when  the 

the  116ff3.tlV6  IS 

universal  (ex-  negative  is  universal,  the  other  is  not  demon- 
ception).  strated,  unless  as  in  former  cases,  if  it  should  be 

assumed  that  the  other  is  present  with  some  individual,  of  what 
this  is  present  with  none,  as  if  A  is  with  no  C,  but  B  with  a 
certain  C,  the  conclusion  is,  that  A  is  not  with  a  certain  B. 
If  then  C  should  be  assumed  present  with  some  individual  of 
that  with  every  one  of  which  A  is  not  present,  it  is  necessary 
that  C  should  be  with  a  certain  B.  We  cannot  however  in 
any  other  way,  converting  the  universal  proposition,  demon- 
strate the  other,  for  there  will  by  no  means  be  a  syllogism.2 

It  appears  then,  that  in  the  first  figure  there  is 
tion  of  the  pre-  a  reciprocal  demonstration  effected  through  the 
ceding  chap-  third  and  through  the  first  figure,  for  when  the 
conclusion  is  affirmative,  it  is  through  the  first, 
but  when  it  is  negative  through  the  last,3  for  it  is  assumed 
*  The  predi-  that  with  what  this  *  is  present  with  none,  the 
cate-  other  f  is  present  with  every  individual.     In  the 

t  The  subject.    mj^ji_e  flgUre  however,  the  syllogism  being  uni- 

1  The  particular  negative. 

2  Thus  in  Ferison,  the  minor,  being  I,  cannot  be  demonstrated  in  a 
circle,  the  conclusion  and  major  being  negative,  except  by  converting 
both  these  into  affirmative.  In  the  cases  of  the  particular  modes  of  the 
third  figure,  where  there  is  an  universal  minor,  i.  e.  Disamis  and  Bokardo, 
there  may  be  a  perfectly  circular  demonstration,  but  not  in  those  which 
have  the  major  universal,  as  Datisi  and  Ferison. 

3  Aristotle  does  not  mean  the  third  figure  of  categoricals,  because  in 
the  syllogisms  mentioned  by  him,  there  are  a  negative  minor  and  an  uni- 
versal conclusion,  contrary  to  the  rules  of  the  third  figure.  He  intends 
therefore  an  hypothetical  syllogism,  wherein  there  are  two  predicates  and 
one  subject,  as  in  the  third  figure. 


CHAP.  VIII.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  199 

versal,  (the  demonstration)  is  through  it  and  through  the  first 
figure,1  and  when  it  is  particular,  both  through  it  and  through 
the  last.2  In  the  third  all  are  through  it,  but  it  is  also  clear 
that  in  the  third  and  in  the  middle  the  syllogisms,  which  are 
not  produced  through  them,  either  are  not  according  to  a 
circular  demonstration,  or  are  imperfect. 

Chap.  VIII. —  Of  Conversion  of  Syllogisms  in  the  first  Figure. 
Conversion  is  by  transposition  of  the  conclusion 

J  r   .   ,  ,  ±.  .         .1.  Definition  of 

to  produce  a  syllogism,  either  that  the  major  is   conversion  of 
not  with  the  middle,  or  this  (the  middle)  is  not  with   gSJ^j. 
the  last  (the  minor  term).3     For  it  is  necessary 
when  the  conclusion  is  converted,  and  one   proposition  re- 
mains, that  the  other  should  be  subverted,  for  if  this  (pro- 
position) will  be,  the  conclusion  will   also  be.4   2  Differerice 
But  there  is  a  difference  whether  we  convert  the   whether  this  is 
conclusion  contradictorily  or  contrarily,  for  there   dictoriiy  or  con- 
is  not  the  same   syllogism,  whichever  way  the   ^Sjfc'tiolte- 
conclusion  is  converted,  and  this  will  appear  from   tween  these 
what  follows.     But  I  mean  to  be  opposed  (con-   shown- 
tradictorily)  between,   to  every  individual  and  not  to  every 
individual,  and  to  a  certain  one  and  not  to  a  certain  one,  and 
contrarily  being  present  with  every  and  being  present  with 
none,  and  with  a  certain  one,  not  with  a  certain   } 
one.5     For  let  A  be  demonstrated  of  C,  through 
the  middle  B  ;  if  then  A  is  assumed  present  with  no  C,  but 
with  every  B,  B  will  be  with  no  C,  and  if  A  is  with  no  C,  but 
B  with  every  C,  A  will  not  be  with  every  B,  and  not  altogether 
with  none,  for  the  universal  was  not  concluded  through  the  last 
figure.     In  a  word,  we  cannot  subvert  universally  the  major 

1  For  the  major  of  Cesare  is  proved  in  Celarent. 

-  For  the  minor  of  Ferison  is  proved  hypothetically.     See  above. 

3  The  minor  term  is  here  called  to  rtXivraiov,  lower  down  in  this 
chapter  it  is  called  to  ta\aTov.  By  transposition  of  the  conclusion,  is 
intended  the  change  of  it  into  its  contradictory  or  contrary,  when  a  pro- 
position is  enunciated,  to  which  the  other  proposition  is  added,  and  thus 
a  new  syllogism  in  subverting  the  former  is  produced.  Vide  Whately  and 
Hill's  Logic. 

4  This  has  been  shown  above,  that  we  cannot  infer  falsity  from  true 
premises ;  if  then  we  admit  the  conclusion  to  be  false,  and  take  its  op- 
posite, one  proposition  must  be  false. 


200  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  it 

premise  by  conversion,  for  it  is  always  subverted  through  the 
third  figure,  but  we  must  assume  both  propositions  to  the 
minor  term,  likewise  also  if  the  syllogism  is  negative.  For 
let  A  be  shown  through  B  to  be  present  with  no  C,  where- 
fore if  A  is  assumed  present  with  every  C,1  but  with  no  B,  B 
will  be  with  no  C,  and  if  A  and  B  are  with  every  C,  A  will 
be  with  a  certain  B,  but  it  was  present  with  none.2 

If  however  the  conclusion  is  converted  contra- 
dictorily, the  (other)  syllogisms  also  will  be  con- 
tradictory,3 and  not  universal,  for  one  premise  is  particular, 
so  that  the  conclusion  will  be  particular.     For  let  the  syllo- 
gism be  affirmative,  and  be  thus  converted,  hence  if  A  is  not 
with  every  C,  but  with  every  B,  B  will  not  be  with  every  C, 
and  if  A  is  not  with  every  C,  but  B  with  every  C,  A  will  not 
be  with  every  B.     Likewise,  if  the  syllogism  be 
e  aren  '    negative,*  for  if  A  is  with  a  certain  C,4  but  with 
t  universally.    no  B,  B  will  not  be  with  a  certain  C,  and  net 
simply  f  with  no  C,  and  if  A  is  with  a  certain  C,5 
and  B  with  every  C,  as  was  assumed  at  first,0  A  will  be  with 
a  certain  B. 

3.  inparticu-  ^n  particular  syllogisms,  when  the  conclusion  is 

lars,  of  the  first    converted  con  tradictorilv,  both  propositions  are  sub- 

figure  whsn  the 

conclusion  is  verted,  but  when  contrarily,  neither  of  them  ;  for  it 
trTdktoniy0""  no  longer  happens,  as  with  universals,  that  through 
both  proposi-      failure  of  the  conclusion7  by  conversion,  a  subver- 

tions  are  sub-         •         ■  j  j       •  'j.i.  1  ,_   •,  a 

verted,  if  con-     S10n  1S  produced,  since  neither  can  we  subvert  its 

lraD!Ty'neither'   at  an-    For  let  A  be  demonstrated  of  a  certain  C,$ 

if  therefore  A  is  assumed  present  with  no  C,9  but 

B  with  a  certain  C,  A  will  not  be  with  a  certain  B,10  and  if  A 

1  i.  e.  by  converse  of  the  conclusion  and  assumption  of  the  minor. 

2  By  hypothesis  in  the  major  premise  of  Celarent. 

3  In  their  opposition,  for  they  will  prove  a  particular  conclusion  contra- 
dicting the  previously  assumed  universal  proposition. 

4  The  subversion  of  the  minor  in  Ferison. 

5  The  subversion  of  the  major  in  Disamis. 
*  In  the  minor  proposition  of  Celarent. 

'  iWuTTovros  tov  ovfi7rtpa(jfiaTog,  deficiente  conclusione.  Buhle. 
This  expression  signifies  the  change  from  an  universal  to  a  particular  in 
the  conclusion,  because  in  the  latter  case  it  comprehends  fewer  things. 

8  Because  there  is  no  syllogism  from  particular  premises. 

9  The  subversion  of  the  minor  in  Camestres — while  the  major  of  the 
first  syllogism  is  retained. 

10  The  contradictory  of  the  major  will  be  concluded. 


CHAP.  IX. J  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  201 

is  with  no  C,  but  with  every  B,  B  will  be  with  no  C,1  so  that  both 
propositions  are  subverted.     If  however  the  con- 
elusion  be  converted  contrarily,  neither  (is  sub- 
verted), for  if  A  is  not  with  a  certain  C,  but  with  every  B,  B 
will  not  be  with  a  certain  C,  but  the  original  proposition  is 
not  yet  subverted,*  for  it  may  be  present  with  a   »  Viz  the  mj_ 
certain  one,  and  not  present  with  a  certain  one.   nor  premise  of 
Of  the  universal  proposition  A  B  there  is  not  any 
syllogism  at  all,2  for  if  A  is  not  with  a  certain  C,  but  is  with  a 
certain  B,  neither  premise  is  universal.      So  also  if  the  syllo- 
gism be  negative,  for  if  A  should  be  assumed  present  with 
every  C,  both  are  subverted,  but  if  with  a  certain  C,  neither  ;• 
the  demonstration  however  is  the  same. 

Chap.  IX. — Of  Co)iversion  of  Syllogisms  in  the  second  Figure. 

Ix  the  second  figure  we  cannot  subvert  the  major 
premise  contrarily,  whichever  way  the  conversion    versais  we  can- 
is  made,  since  the  conclusion  will  always  be  in  the   not  infer  th1 

'  1  contrary  to  the 

third  figure,  but  there  was  not  in  this  figure  an   major  premise, 
universal  syllogism.      The  other  proposition  in-   ^  ^ntTadic- 
deed  we  shall  subvert  similarly  to  the  conversion,    tory— the  mi- 

I,  .     M      i       ./»   ,v  •  t       nor  dependent 

mean  by  similarly,  it  the  conversion  is  made   upon  the  as- 

contrarily  (we  shall  subvert  it  contrarily),  but  if  sumption  of  the 

t  •!      i  t     •  -n        i         a  a   i        conclusion. 

contradictorily  by  contradiction,     tor  let  A6  be 
with  every  B  and  with  no  C,  the  conclusion  B  C,  if  then  B 
is  assumed4  present  with  every  C,  and  the  proposition  A  B 
remains,  A  will  be  with  every  C,  for  there  is  the  first  figure. 
If  however  B  is  5  with  every  C,  but  A  with  no  C,  A   9 
is  not  with  every  B,  the  last  figure.     If  then  B  C 
(the  conclusion)  be  converted  contradictorily,  A  B  may  be  de- 
monstrated similarly,6  and  A  C  contradictorily.     For  if  B  is 
with  a  certain  C,7  but  A  with  no  C,  A  will  not  be  present, 
with  a  certain  B  ;  again,  if  B  8  is  with  a  certain  C,  but  A 

1  That  is,  by  assuming  a  contradictory  conclusion  of  the  first  syllo- 
gism, and  retaining  the  major  premise  of  the  same,  a  conclusion  will  be 
drawn,  contradictory  of  the  minor. 

2  In  which  the  major  premise  of  Darii  is  subverted. 

3  This  is  inCamesires.     4   Barbara  subverting  the  minor  of  Camestres. 
i  Felapton  subverting  the  major  of  Camestres. 

8  i.  e.  subverted  by  a  contrary. 

7  Darii  subverting  the  minor.  8  Ferison  subverting  the  major. 


202  aristotle's  organon.  [book  ii. 

with  every  B,  A  is  with  a  certain  C,  so  that  there  is  a  syllo- 

3  gism  produced  contradictorily.1     In  like  manner 

it  can  be  shown,  if  the  premises  are  vice  versa,2 

lar^ifthe  con  ^ut  ^  tne  syn°gism  is  particular,  the  conclusion 
trar'yofthe  being  converted  contrarily,  neither  premise  is 
as"umeSd\nei-  subverted,  as  neither  was  it  in  the  first  figure,  (if 
ther proposi-  however  the  conclusion  is)  contradictorily  (con- 
vened ;  if  the  verted),  both  (are  subverted).  For  let  A  be  as- 
Do"hrareCtory'  sumed  present  with  no  B,  but  with  a  (certain)  C,3 
the  conclusion  B  C  ;  if  then  B  is  assumed  present 
with  a  certain  C,  and  A  B  remains,  the  conclusion  will  be 
that  A  is  not  present  with  a  certain  C,  but  the  original  would 
not  be  subverted,  for  it  may  and  may  not  be  present  with  a 
certain  individual.  Again,  if  B  is  with  a  certain  C,  and  A 
with'  a  certain  C,  there  will  not  be  a  syllogism,  for  neither  of 
the  assumed  premises  is  universal,  wherefore  A  B  is  not  sub- 
verted. If  however  the  conversion  is  made  contradictorily, 
both  are  subverted,  since  if  B  is  with  every  C,  but  A  with  no 
B,  A  is  with  no  C,  it  was  however  present  with  a  certain  (C).3 
Again,  if  B  is  with  every  C,  but  A  with  a  certain  C,  A  will  be 
with  a  certain  B,  and  there  is  the  same  demonstration,  if  the 
universal  proposition  be  affirmative. 

Chap.  X. — Of  the  same  in  the  third  Figure. 

1  in  this  figure,   *N  tne  tn*r<i  &%nre>  when  the  conclusion  is  con- 
if  the  contrary'   verted  contrarily,  neither  premise  is  subverted, 

sion^ass'um-  according  to  any  of  the  Syllogisms,  but  When  COn- 
ed,  neither  tradictorily,  both  are  in  all  the  modes.  For  let 
ver^d.VuUf  A  be  shown  to  be  with  a  certain  B,  and  let  C  be 
tory^bo'th"3'0"  taken  as  the  middle,  and  the  premises  be  universal : 
if  then  A  is  assumed  not  present  with  a  certain 
B,  but  B  with  every  C,  there  is  no  syllogism  of  A  and  C,4 

1.  universal.    nor  if"  A  is  not  Present  witn  a  certain  B,  but  with 

every  C,  will  there  be  a  syllogism  of  B  and  C.5 

There  will  also  be  a  similar  demonstration,  if  the  premises 

1  Because  Darii  proves  a  contradictory  conclusion  to  the  minor,  and 
Ferison  a  contradictory  conclusion  to  the  major — of  the  same  Camestres. 

2  That  is,  if  the  major  is  negative,  but  the  minor  affirmative,  hence  a 
syllogism  produced  in  Cesare. 

3  A  was  assumed  present  with  a  certain  C,  in  the  minor  of  Festino. 

*  Because  the  major  is  particular.      5  Because  the  major  is  particular. 


CHAP.  X.]  THE   PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  203 

are  not  universal,  for  either  both  must  be  particular  by  con- 
version, or  the  universal  be  joined  to  the  minor,  but  thus 
there  was  not  a  syllogism  neither  in  the  first  nor  in  the  middle 
figure.     If  however  they  are  converted  contra-   , 
dictorily,  both  propositions  are   subverted  ;    for 
if  A  is  with  no  B,  but  B  with  every  C,  A  will  be  with  no  C  ; 
again,  if  A  is  with  no  B,  but  with  every  C,  B  will  be  with  no 
C.     In  like  manner  if  one  proposition  is  not  uni- 
versal ;  since  if  A  is  with  no  B,  but  B  with  a 
certain  C,  A  will  not  be  with  a  certain  C,  but  if  A  is  with 
no  B,  but  with  every  C,  B  will  be  present  with  no  C.     So 
also  if  the  syllogism  be  negative,  for  let  A  be  shown  not  pre- 
sent with  a  certain  B,  and  let  the  affirmative  proposition  be 
B  C,  but  the  negative  A  C,  for  thus  there  was  a  syllogism  ; 
when  then  the  proposition  is  taken  contrary  to  the  conclusion, 
there  will  not  be  a  syllogism.     For  if  A  were  with  a  certain 
B,  but  B  with  every  C,  there  was  not  a  syllogism   # 
of  A  and  C,*1  nor  if  A  were  with  a  certain  B,   t>.  i.  Anai.'pr! 
but  with  no  C  was  there  a  syllogism  of  B  and  C,t    +  Vide  ch-  v- 

hi   Anal    Pr 

so  that  the  propositions  are  not  subverted.  When 

however  the  contradictory  (of  the  conclusion  is 

assumed)  they  are  subverted.     For  if  A  is  with 

every  B,  and  B  with  C,  A  will  be  with  every  C,    *  camestres. 

but  it  wa3  with  none.2    Again  if  A  $  is  with  every 

B,  but  with  no  C,  B  will  be  with  no  (J,  but  it  was  with  every  C.3 

There  is  a  similar  demonstration  also,  if  the  pro-   2.  particulars 

positions  are  not  universal^  for  A  C  II  becomes   the  same. 

.  .  "  .  §  Ferison 

universal  negative,  but  the  other, ^f  particular  af-    u  The  major 
firmative.     If  then  A  is  with  every  B,  but  B  with  PJ0''; 

/       '  IT  The  minor 

a  certain  C,  A  happens  to  a  certain  C,  but  it  was   pr 
with  none  ;4  again,  if  A  is  with  every  B,  but  with  no   *  Ca™estres- 
C,*  B  is  with  no  C,  but  if  A  is  with  a  certain  B,  and  B  with  a 
certain  C,  there  is  no  syllogism,5  nor  if  A  is  with  a  certain  B, 
but  with  no  C,  (will  there  thus  be  a  syllogism):0    .  „,. 

,v  ,    ,  .         i  .     j.     r  t  The  contra- 

^^^nce  in  that  way,j  but  not  in  this,|  the  pro-   dictory. 
positions  are  subverted.  I  The  contrary. 

1  Because  the  major  is  particular, 

8  So  .assumed  in  the  major  proposition  of  Felapton. 

3  In  the  minor  of  Felapton. 

*  In  the  major  of  Ferison.  s  Because  of  part,  premises. 

6  Because  of  the  part,  major. 


204  aristotle's  org  anon.  [book  ii. 

From  what  has  been  said  then  it  seems  clear 
tioifeCai"tUla"  how,  when  the  conclusion  is  converted,  a  syllogism 
arises  in  each  figure,  both  when  contrarily  and 
when  contradictorily  to  the  proposition,  and  that  in  the  first 
figure  syllogisms  are  produced  through  the  middle  and  the 
last,  and  the  minor  premise  is  always  subverted  through  the 
middle  (figure),  but  the  major  by  the  last  (figure)  :  in  the  se- 
cond figure,  however,  through  the  first  and  the  last,  and  the 
minor  premise  (is)  always  (subverted)  through  the  first  figure, 
but  the  major  through  the  last :  but  in  the  third  (figure) 
through  the  first  and  through  the  middle,  and  the  major  pre- 
mise is  always  (subverted)  through  the  first,  but  the  minor 
premise  through  the  middle  (figure).  What  therefore  con- 
version is,  and  how  it  is  effected  in  each  figure,  also  what 
syllogism  is  produced,  has  been  shown. 

Chap.  XI. —  Of  Deduction  to  the  Impossible  in  the  first  Figure. 

1   Howsyiio-  -A-  syllogism  through  the  impossible  is  shown, 

gism  iia  -rpv  when  the  contradiction  of  the  conclusion  is  laid 

shown,°and  its  down,  and  another  proposition  is  assumed,  and  it 

distinction  js  produced  in  all  the  figures,  for  it  is  like  conver- 

from  conver-  *■  ° 

sion  (aur<-  sion  except  that  it  differs  insomuch  as  that  it  is 

oTpo<pn)-  converted   indeed,  when   a  syllogism   has   been 

made,  and  both  propositions  have  been  assumed,  but  it  is  de- 
duced to  the  impossible,  when  the  opposite  is  not  previously 
acknowledged  but  is  manifestly  true.  Now  the  terms  subsist 
similarly !  in  both,  the  assumption  also  of  both  is  the  same,  as 
for  instance,  if  A  is  present  with  every  B,  but  the  middle  is 
C,  if  A  is  supposed  present  with  every  or  with  no  B,  but  with 
every  C,  which  was  true,  it  is  necessary  that  C  should  be  with 
no  or  not  with  every  B.  But  this  is  impossible,  so  that 
the  supposition  is  false,  wherefore  the  opposite  2  is  true.  It 
is  a  similar  case  with  other  figures,  for  whatever  are  capable 
of  conversion,  are  also  capable  of  the  syllogism  per  impossibile. 
2.  The  univer-  All  other  problems  then  are  demonstrated 
the  fi^t'figure  tnrough  the  impossible  in  all  the  figures,  but  the 
not  demonstra-   universal  affirmative  is  demonstrated  in  the  mid- 

1  That  is  to  say,  both  in  the  converse  syllogism  and  in  that  per  impos- 
sibile. z  The  contradictory. 


CHAP.    XI.~|  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  205 


-i 


die,  and  in  the  third,  but  is  not  in  the  first.  For  Me  per  impo;- 
let  A  be  supposed  not  present  with  every  B,  or  slbUe- 
present  with  no  B,  and  let  the  other  proposition  be  assumed 
from  either  part,  whether  C  is  present  with  every  A,  or  B 
with  every  D,  for  thus  there  will  be  the  first  figure.  If  then 
A  is  supposed  not  present  with  every  B,  there  is  no  syllo- 
gism,1 from  whichever  part  the  proposition  is  assumed,  but  if 
(it  is  supposed  that  A  is  present  with)  no  (B),  when  the  pro- 
position B  D  is  assumed,  there  will  indeed  be  a  syllogism  of 
the  false,  but  the  thing  proposed  is  not  demonstrated.  For  if 
A  is  with  no  B,  but  B  with  every  D,  A  will  be  with  no  D, 
but  let  this  be  impossible,  therefore  it  is  false  that  A  is  with 
no  B.  If  however  it  is  false  that  it  is  present  with  no  B,  it 
does  not  follow  that  it  is  true  that  it  is  present  with  every  B. 
But  if  C  A  is  assumed,  there  is  no  syllogism,2  neither  when 
A  is  supposed  not  present  with  every  B,  so  that  it  is  manifest 
that  the  being  present  with  every,  is  not  demonstrated  in  the 
first  figure  per  impossibile.  But  to  be  present  with  a  certain 
one,  and  with  none,  and  not  with  every  is  de-  3  Butthepar 
monstrated,  for  let  A  be  supposed  present  with  affir.  and  univ. 
no  B,  but  let  B  be  assumed  to  be  present  with  demonstrated, 
every  or  with  a  certain  C,  therefore  is  it  neces-   ^h™  tne  c°n- 

i  iiii  -i  -i  tradictory  of 

sary  that  A  should  be  with  no  or  not  with  every  the  conclusion 
C,  but  this  is  impossible,  for  let  this  be  true  and  isassumed- 
manifest,  that  A  is  with  every  C,  so  that  if  this  is  false,  it 
is  necessary  that  A  should  be  with  a  certain  B.  But  if 
one  proposition  should  be  assumed  to  A,3  there  will  not  be 
a  syllogism,4  neither  when  the  contrary  to  the  conclusion  is 
supposed  as  not  to  be  with  a  certain  one,  wherefore  it  appears 
that  the  contradictory  must  be  supposed.  Again,  let  A  be  sup- 
posed present  with  a  certain  B,  and  C  assumed  present  with 
every  A,  then  it  is  necessary  that  C  should  be  with  a  certain  B, 
but  let  this  be  impossible,  hence  the  hypothesis  is  false,  and 
if   this   be   the  case,  that  A   is   present  with  no  B   is   true. 

1   Because  of  a  particular  nega.  prem.  being  inadmissible  in  the  first  fig. 
-  Because  from  the  hypothesis  being  negative  it  eainioc  be  the  minor 
in  the  first  fig. 

3  So  that  it  becomes  the  major. 

4  Because  the  negative  hypothesis  becomes  the  minor  prem.  contrary 
to  the  rule. 


206  Aristotle's  okganon.  "book  n. 

In  like  manner,  if  C  A  is  assumed  negative ;  if  however  the 
proposition  be  assumed  to  B,  there  will  not  be  a  syllogism, 
but  if  the  contrary  be  supposed,  there  will  be  a  syllogism,  and 
the  impossibile  (demonstration),  but  what  was  proposed  will 
not  be  proved.  For  let  A  be  supposed  present  with  every  B, 
and  let  C  be  assumed  present  with  every  A,  then  it  is  neces- 
sary that  C  should  be  with  every  B,  but  this  is  impossible,  so 
that  it  is  false  that  A  is  with  every  B,  but  it  is  not  yet  neces- 
sary that  if  it  is  not  present  with  every,  it  is  present  with  no 
B.  The  same  will  happen  also  if  the  other  proposition 1  is 
assumed  to  B,  for  there  will  be  a  syllogism,  and  the  impossible 
(will  be  proved),  but  the  hypothesis  is  not  subverted,  so  that 
the  contradictory  must  be  supposed.  In  order  however  to 
prove  that  A  is  not  present  with  every  B,  it  must  be  supposed 
4  Ms  the  ar  Presenfc  with  every  B,  for  if  A  is  present  with 
neg.  is  demon-  every  B,  and  C  with  every  A,  C  will  be  with 
tneatsudb'-coUnt-lf  every  B.  so  that  if  this  impossible,  the  hypothesis 
trary  to  the  is  false.  In  the  same  manner,  if  the  other  proposi- 
assumed,  what  tion  is  assumed  to  B,2  also  if  C  A  is  negative  in 
ruabvPertedSed 'S  *^e  same  way>  f°r  tnus  there  is  a  syllogism,  but  if 
the  negative  be  applied  to  B,  there  is  no  demon- 
stration. If  however  it  should  be  supposed  not  present  with 
every,  but  with  some  one,  there  is  no  demonstration  that  it  is 
not  present  with  every,  but  that  it  is  present  with  none,  for  if 
A  is  with  a  certain  B,  but  C  with  every  A,  C  will  be  with  a 
certain  B,  if  then  this  is  impossible  it  is  false  that  A  is  present 
with  a  certain  B,  so  that  it  is  true  that  it  is  present  with  none. 
This  however  being  demonstrated,  what  is  true  is  subverted 
besides,  for  A  was  present  with  a  certain  B,  and  with  a  cer- 
tain one  was  not  present.  Moreover,  the  impossibile  does  not 
result  from  the  hypothesis,  for  it  would  be  false,  since  we 
cannot  conclude  the  false  from  the  true,  but  now  it  is  true, 
for  A  is  with  a  certain  B,  so  that  it  must  not  be  supposed  pre- 
sent with  a  certain,  but  with  every  B.  The  like  also  will 
occur,  if  we  should  show  that  A  is  not  present  with  a  certain 
B,  since  if  it  is  the  same  thing  not  to  be  with  a  certain  indi- 
vidual, and  to  be  not  with  every,  there  is  the  same  demon- 
stration of  both. 

1  A  proposition  evidently  true. 

2  If  the  true  proposition  becomes  the  minor. 


CHAP.  XII.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  207 

It  appears  then,  that  not  the  contrary,  but  the 

\.r  ,  i   •         11         11       •  i     »•   Summary 

contradictory  must  be  supposed  in  all  syllogisms,1   and  reason  of 
for  thus  there  will  be  a  necessary  (consequence),    su^p'tiJn.88" 
and  a  probable  axiom,2  for  if  of  every  thing  af- 
firmation or  negation  (is  true),  when  it  is  shown  that  negation 
is  not,  affirmation  must  necessarily  be  true.     Again,  except  it 
is  admitted  that  affirmation  is  true,  it  is  fitting  to  admit  nega- 
tion ;  but  it  is  in  neither  way  fitting  to  admit  the  contrary,  for 
neither,  if  the  being  present  with  no  one  is  false,  is  the  being 
present  with  every  one  necessarily  true,  nor  is  it  probable 
that  if  the  one  is  false  the  other  is  true. 

It  is  palpable,  therefore,  that  in  the  first  figure,  all  other 
problems  are  demonstrated  through  the  impossible ;  but  that 
the  universal  affirmative  is  not  demonstrated. 

Chap.  XII. — Of  the  same  in  the  second  Figure. 
In  the  middle,  however,  and  last  figure,  this3  also 

*-'  In  the  second 

is  demonstrated.    For  let  A  be  supposed  not  pre-   figure  a  is 
sent  with  every  B,  but  let  A  be  supposed  present   K£*g£ 
with  every  C.  therefore  if  it  is  not  present  with   contradictory  is 
every  B,  but  is  with  every  C,  C  is  not  with  every   "omra"^!* 
B,  but  this  is  impossible,  for  let  it  be  manifest 
that  C  is  with  every  B,  wherefore  what  was  supposed  is  false, 
and  the  being  present  with  every  individual  is  true.    If  how- 
ever the  contrary  be  supposed,  there  will  be  a  syllogism,  and 
the  impossible,  yet  the  proposition  is  not  demonstrated.     For 
if  A  is  present  with  no  B,  but  with  every  C,  C  will   % 
be  with  no  B,  but  this  is  impossible,  hence  that  A 

1  Leading  to  the  impossible.  Taylor  gives  rise  to  much  confusion,  by 
using  the  word  opposite  as  antithetical  to  contrary,  instead  of  the  word 
contradictory. 

2  aliwfia  tvSoKov—  dignitas  probabilis,  Averr.— axioma  rationi  con- 
sentaneum,  Buhle ;  the  latter  notes,  that  Aristotle  refers  to  the  principle, 
that  of  two  contradictories,  one  is  true  and  the  other  false,  from  which  it 
follows  that  when  the  contradictory  of  the  first  conclusion  is  proved 
false,  the  original  conclusion  itself  is  proved  true.  As  to  the  words  them- 
selves, it  may  be  sufficient  to  remark,  that  dKidifJ-ara  are  the  original  pre- 
mises, from  which  demonstration  proceeds,  and  are  a  branch  of ^  the 
Koiva'i  'Ap\ai ;  and  that  taken  purely,  per  se,  Aristotle  regards  to.  tvc6$a 
as  among  the  elements  of  syllogism,  some  of  wliich  are  necessary.  See 
also  Waitz,  vol.  i.  p.  505. 

3  An  universal  affirmative. 


208  aristotle's  orgaxox.  [book  ii 

is  with  no  B  is  false.      Still  it  does  not  follow,  that  if  this  is 

false,  the  being  present  with  every  B  is  true,  but  when  A  is 

with  a  certain  B,  let  A  be  supposed  present  with 

no  B,  but  with  every  C,  therefore  it  is  necessary 

that  C  should  be  with  no  B,  so  that  if  this  is  impossible  A  must 

necessarily  be  present  with  a  certain  B.     Still 

if  it*   is  supposed   not   present  with   a  certain 

one,j"  there  will  be  the  same  '  as  in  the  first  figure. 

Again,  let  A  be  supposed  pi'esent  with  a  certain  B,  but  let  it 

be  with  no  C,  it  is  necessarv  then  that  C  should  not  be  with 

a  certain  B,  but  it  was  with  every,  so  that  the  supposition  is 

false,  A  then  will  be  with  no  B.  When  however  A 

is  not  with  every  B,  let  it  be  supposed  present  with 

every  B,  but  with  no  C,  therefore  it  is  necessary  that  C  should 

be  with  no  B,  and  this  is  impossible,  wherefore  it  is  true  that 

A  is  not  with  every  B.     Evidently  then  all  syllogisms  are 

produced  through  the  middle  figure.2 

Chap.     XIII. —  Of  the  same  in  the  third  Figure. 

1  in  this  figure  Through  the  last  figure  also,  (it  will  be  con- 
both  affirma-  eluded)  in  a  similar  way.  For  let  A  be  supposed 
tives  are  de-ga"  not  present  with  a  certain  B,  but  C  present  with 
monstrabie  per   every  B,  A  then  is  not  with  a  certain  C,  and  if 

absurdum.  ....  .,,..„,  , 

this  is  impossible,  it  is  raise  that  A  is  not  with  a 
certain  B,  wherefore  that  it  is  present  with  every  B  is  true. 
If,  again,  it  should  be  supposed  present  with  none,  there 
will  be  a  syllogism,  and  the  impossible,  but  the  proposition  is 
not  proved,  for  if  the  contrary  is  supposed  there  will  be  the 
same3  as  in  the  former  (syllogisms).  But  in  order  to  con- 
clude that  it  is  present  with  a  certain  one,  this  hypothesis 
must  be  assumed,  for  if  A  is  with  no  B,  but  C  with  a  certain 
B,  A  will  not  be  with  every  C,  if  then  this  is  false,  it  is 
true  that  A  is  with  a  certain  B.  But  when  A  is  with  no 
B,  let  it  be  supposed  present  with  a  certain  one,  and  let  C  be 
assumed  present  with  every  B,  wherefore  it  is  necessary  that 
A  should  be  with  a  certain  C,  but  it  was  with  no  C,  so  that  it 
is  false  that  A  is  with  a  certain  B.  If  however  A  is  supposed 

1  The  proposition  will  not  be  so  much  confirmed  as  subverted,  for  if  O 
is  false,  A  is  true,  and  vice  versa.  -   By  a  deduction  to  an  absurdity. 

3  A  will  not  be  demonstrated  universal,  I  ut  particular. 


CHAP,  XIV."|  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS:  209 

present  with  every  B,  the  proposition  is  not  demonstrated,1 
but  in  order  to  its  not  being  present  with  every,  this  hypothesis 
must  be  taken.2  For  if  A  is  with  every  B,  and  C  with  a  cer- 
tain B,  A  is  with  a  certain  C,  but  this  was  not  so,  hence  it  is 
false  that  it  is  with  every  one,  and  if  thus,  it  is  true  that  it 
is  not  with  every  B,  and  if  it  is  supposed  present  with  a  cer- 
tain B,  there  will  be  the  same  things  as  in  the  syllogisms 
above  mentioned. 

It  appears  then  that  in  all  syllogisms  through 
the  impossible  the  contradictory  must  be  supposed,   t2i-0n.ecapitula" 
and  it  is  apparent  that  in  the  middle  figure  the 
affirmative  is  in  a  certain  way3  demonstrated, and  the  universal 
in  the  last  figure. 


Chap.  XIV. — Of  the  difference  beticeen  the  Ostensive,  and  the 
Deduction  to  the  Impossible.* 

A  DEMONSTRATION  to  the    impossible  differs  from     i.  Difference 

an  ostensive,  in  that  it  admits  what  it  wishes  to   |£SSSti2ta? 
subvert,  leading  to  an   acknowledged    falsehood,   and  that  per 
but    the     ostensive    commences   from   confessed   imP0Sslblle- 
theses.      Both    therefore  assume    two  allowed  propositions, 
but  the  one  5  assumes  those  from  which  the  syllogism  is  formed, 
and  the  other0  one  of  these,  and  the  contradictory  of  the  con- 
clusion.     In   the  one  case*  also  the  conclusion 
need  not  be  known,  nor  previously  assumed  that   sive 
it  is,  or  that  it  is  not,  but  in  the  other  it  is  neces- 
sary7 (previously  to  assume)  that  it  is  not ;  it  is  of  no  conse- 
quence  however  whether   the    conclusion    is   affirmative   or 

1  Because  if  A  is  with  every  B  is  false,  that  A  is  with  no  B  is  not  im- 
mediately true,  but  only  the  particular  negative  is  true. 

2  A,  i.  e.  the  hypothesis  of  being  universally  present. 

3  By  a  deduction  to  an  absurdity. 

4  Compare  Prior  Anal.  i.  23;  Hessey'sLogicalTables.No.  4 ;  Whately's 
Treatise  on  Rhetoric,  part  i.  c.  3 ;  Rhetoric,  xi.  22.  It  is  clear  from  the 
remark  in  the  text,  that  the  demonstration  per  impossibile  is  one  kind  of 
the  hypothetical  syllogism,  the  object  of  which  is  to  prove  the  truth  of  a 
problem,  by  inferring  a  falsity  from  its  contradiction  being  assumed. 
(Vide  An.  i.  23,  and  29;  also  Waitz,  vol.  i.  p.  430.)  The  reader  will  find 
llie  question  fully  discussed  in  note  G,  Appendix  to  Mitchell's  Logic. 

5  The  ostensive.  6  The  per  impossibile. 

7  i.  e.  we  must  assume  the  contradictory  of  the  concision,  to  be 
proved. 

v 


210  Aristotle's  org  anon.  [book  ii. 

negative,  but  it  will  happen  the  same  about  both.1  New 
whatever  is  concluded  ostensively  can  also  be  proved  per  im- 
possibile,  and  what  is  concluded  per  impossibile  may  be  shown 
ostensively  through  the  same  terms,  but  not  in  the  same  figures. 
For  when  the  syllogism2  is  in  the  first  figure,3  the 

monst'ratld  p«  truth  wil1  be  in  tne  middle,  or  in  the  last,  the  ne- 

absurdum  in  gative  indeed  in  the  middle,  but  the  affirmative 

is'prored inthe  i°  the  last.     When  however  the  syllogism  is  in 

second  osten-  the  middle  figure,4  the  truth  will  be  in  the  first  in 

tiively,  if  the  n     i  ,  ,  \  ,  ,  ,,  ... 

problem  be  ne-   all  the  problems,  but  when  the  syllogism  is  in  the 

fh^thirdflgire   last'  the  truth  wil1  be  in  tne  first  and  in  the  mid" 
if  it  be  affirm-     die,  affirmatives  in  the  first,  but  negatives  in  the 

l/^barii.         middle.     For  let  it  be  demonstrated  through  the 

first  figure*  that  A  is  present  with  no,  or  not  with 

every  B,  the  hypothesis  then  was  that  A  is  with  a  certain  B, 

but  C  was  assumed  present  with  every  A,  but  with  no  B,  for 

thus  there  was  a  syllogism,  and  also  the  impossible.      But 

this  is  the  middle  figure,  if  C  is  with  every  A,  but  with  no  B, 

and  it  is  evident  from  these  that  A  is  with  no  B.     Likewise  if  it 

2   t  Barbara      bas  been  demonstrated  to  be  not  with  every, j-  for 

the  hypothesis  is  that  it  is  with  every,  but  C  was 

assumed  present  with  every  A,  but  not  with  every  B.     Also 

in  a  similar  manner  if  C  A  were  assumed  negative,  for  thus 

also  there  is  the  middle  figure.!   .  Again,  let  A  be 

Festino.  shown  present  with  a  certain  B,§  the  hypothesis 

rent.InCela  tnen  ls>  tnat  **  1S  Present  >vith  none,  but  B  was 
assumed  to  be  with  every  C,  and  A  to  be  with 

every  or  with  a  certain  C,  for  thus  (the  conclusion)  will  be 

5  ii  Dara  ti  impossible,  but  this  is  the  last  figure,  if  A  and  B  || 
are  with  every  C.     From  these  then  it  appears 

that  A  must  necessarily  be  with  a  certain  B,  and  similarly  if 

B  or  A  is  assumed  present  with  a  certain  C. 

«  n  Baroko  Again,  ^et  ^  De  shown  in  the  middle  figure^" 

that  A  is  with  every  B,  then  the  hypothesis  was 

that  A  is  not  with  every  B,  but  A  was  assumed  present  with 

1  The  conclusion  is  called  negative  when  it  is  false,  whether  it  affirms 
cr  denies,  hence  if  it  affirm  a  falsity,  it  is  said  "not  to  be,"  and  when  it 
denies  a  truth,  it  is  equally  said  "  not  to  be."  Waitz  omits  "  not"  in 
the  same  figures ;  I  read  with  Bekker,  Buhle,  and  Taylor. 

2  Per  impossibile.         3  The  thing  proposed  will  be  proved. — Taylor. 

4  Sometimes  also  in  the  3rd,  in  fact  what  Arist.  here  states  are  the  prin- 
cipal modes  of  demonstration,  and  are  not  tc  be  too  generally  assumed. 


CHAP.  XIV.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  211 

every  C,  and  C  with  every  B,  for  thus  there  will  be  the  im- 
possible.    And  this  is  the  first  figure,*  if  A  is   7  »  Barbara 
with  every  C,  and  C  with  every  B.     Likewise  if 
it  is  demonstrated  to  be  present  with  a  certain  one,f   8"  +  Caraestres- 
for  the  hypothesis  was  that  A  was  with  no  B,  but  A  was  as- 
sumed present  with  every  C,  and  C  with  a  certain  B,  but  if 
the  syllogism  J  should  be  negative,1  the  hypothesis   9  +  Festino  in. 
was  that  A  is  with  a  certain  B,  for  A  was  assumed    ferring  the  im- 
to  be  with  no  C,  and  C  with  every  B,  so  that   v°bS1  e' 
there  is  the  first  figure.     Also  if  in  like  manner  the  syllo- 
gism §  is  not  universal,  but  A  is  demonstrated  not 
to  be  with  a  certain  B,||  for  the  hypothesis  was   sibtie.  imp°s 
that  A  is  with  every  B,  but  A  was  assumed  present   10-  U  in  cesare. 
with  no  C.  and  C  with  a  certain  B,  for  thus  there   _      . 
is  the  first  figure.^ 

Again,  in  the  third  figure,*  let  A  be  shown  to     .  _,  „  ,     , 
be  with  every  B,   therefore  the  hypothesis  was 
that  A  is  not  with  every  B,  but  C  has  been  assumed  to  be 
with  every  B,  and  A  with  every  C,  for  thus  there  will  be  the 
impossible,  but  this  is  the  first  figure.^     Likewise 
also,  if  the  demonstration  is  in  a  certain  thing,2  J 
for  the  hypothesis  would  be  that  A  is  with  no  B,    + 
but  C  has  been  assumed  present  with  a  certain  B,  and  A  with 
every  C,  but  if  the  syllogism  is  negative, §  the  by- 
pothesis  is  that  A  is  with  a  certain  B,  but  C  has 
been  assumed  present  with  no  A,  but  with  every  B,  and  this 
is  the  middle  figure.     In  like  manner  also,3  if  the  demonstra- 
tion is  not  ||  universal,  since  the  hypothesis  will 
be  that  A  is  with  every  B,  and  C  has  been  as-        n    dtlS1- 
sumed  present  with  no  A,  but  with  a  certain  B,    «  Festino 
and  this  is  the  middle  figure.^ 

It  is  evident  then  that  we  may  demonstrate  3.  what  is  de- 
each  of  the  problems  through  the  same  terms,  both  "^"rdumls'so 
ostensively4  and  through  the  impossible,  and  in   also  ostensive- 

1  If  it  should  prove  a  conclusion  in  E,  which  contradicts  the  minor  of 
Festino. 

2  This  will  prove  a  conclusion  in  I. 

3  If  the  syllogism  per  impossible  in  Datisi  should  prove  O. 

4  Buhle,  Bekker,  and  Taylor  insert  "  and  through  the  impossible,"  which 
Waitz  omits.  It  may  be  remarked,  that  though  in  some  cases  the  demon- 
stration per  impossibile  is  advantageous,  yet  that  it  is  more  open  to 
fallacy,   especially  to    tliat   of    "a   non-causa  pro  causa,"  a  deception 

p  2 


212  Aristotle's  org  anon,       [book  n. 

iy,  and  vice  like  manner  it  will  be  possible  when  the  syllo- 
vers5-  gisms  are  ostensive,  to  deduce  to  the  impossible  in 

the  assumed  terms  when  the  proposition  is  taken  contradic- 
tory to  the  conclusion.  For  the  same  syllogisms  arise  as  those 
through  conversion,  so  that  we  have  forthwith  figures  through 
which  each  (problem)  will  be  (concluded).  It  is  clear  then 
that  every  problem  is  demonstrated  by  both  modes,  (viz.)  by 
the  impossible  and  ostensively,  and  we  cannot  possibly  separ- 
ate the  one  from  the  other. 


Chap.  XV. —  Of  the  Method  of  concluding  from  Opposites  in  tJie 

several  Figures. 

In  what  figure  then  we  may,  and  in  what  we  may 
Jus°flguTesVari  not'  syllogize  from  opposite  propositions1  will  be 
from  which  a  manifest  thus,  and  I  say  that  opposite  propositions 
duciWeTrom  are  according  to  diction  four,  as  for  instance  (to 
opposite  pro-  ^g  present)  with  every  (is  opposed)  to  (to  be  pre- 
latter  («ara  tij»  sent)  with  none  ;  and  (to  be  present)  with  every 
kinii1,°(cfrr  t0  (t0  be  present)  not  with  every  ;  and  (to  be  pre- 
Herm.  ?,)  but  sent)  with  a  certain  one  to  (to  be  present  with) 
«"u.,,Tot"  three,    no  one  ;  and  (to  be  present  with)  a  certain  one  to 

(to  be  present)  not  with  a  certain  one  ;  in  truth 
however  they  are  three,  for  (to  be  present)  with  a  certain  one 

which  is  very  frequent  in  dialectical  disputation  when  the  opponent  is 
a.sked  to  grant  certain  premises.  Vide  the  17th  ch.  of  this  book,  also 
Rhet.  ii.  24. 

1  avriicufiivai  irporaaHQ,  is  an  expression  sometimes  limited  to  con- 
tradictories, the  Kara  n)v  Xsfiv,  opposition  is  properly  subcontrary  :  that 
of  subalterns  is  not  recognised  by  Aristotle  {inra\\r]Koi) ;  the  laws  of  this 
last  are  first  given  by  Apuleius  de  Dogmate  Plat.  lib.  iii.  anonymously  ; 
also  by  Marcian  Capella.  Vide  Whately's  and  Hill's  Logic.  Taylor, 
from  his  extreme  fondness  for  the  expression  'opposites,"  certainly  does 
not  "  what  is  dark  in  this,  il'.bmine,  ncr  what  is  low,  raise  and  support ." 

Ex.  1.  Every  science  is  excellent 
No  science  is  excellent 
•  • .  No  science  is  science. 

Ex.  2.  Every  science  is  excellent 

No  medicine  (a  certain  science)  is  excellent 
.  • .  No  medicine  (a  certain  science)  is  science. 

Ex.  3.  No  science  is  opinion 

All  medicine  (a  certain  science)  is  opinion 
.  • .  No  medicine  (a  certain  science)  is  science. 


CHAP.  XV.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  213 

is  opposed  to  (being  present)  not  with  a  certain  one  accord- 
ing to  expression  only.  But  of  these  I  call  such  contraries 
as  are  universal,  viz.  the  being  present  with  every,  and  (the 
being  present)  with  none,  as  for  instance,  that  every  science 
is  excellent  to  no  science  is  excellent,  but  I  call  the  others 
contradictories. 

In  the  first  figure  then  there  is  no  syllogism   2.  No  conciu- 
frora  contradictory  propositions,  neither  affirma-    s!°n  f™ .°,Ppo" 

J    *      r  _       sites  of  either 

tive   nor  negative  :    not  affirmative,  because  it   kind  in  the 
is   necessary   that    both   propositions   should    be     rs    gure' 
affirmative,  but  affirmation  and  negation  are  contradictories : 
nor  negative,  because  contradictories  affirm  and  deny  the  same 
thing  of  the  same.*  but  the  middle  in  the  first 

*  \riHp  Aid- 

figure  is  not  predicated  of  both  (extremes),  but   rich's  logic,  ch. 
one  thing  is  denied  of  it,  and  it  is  predicated  of  Eiln'ch^s1*' 
another  ;  these  propositions  however  are  not  con- 
tradictory. 

But  in  the  middle  figure  it  is  possible  to  pro-    3  Butfrom 
duce  a  syllogism  both  from  contradictories   and   both  in  the  . 
from  contraries,  for  let  A  be  good,  but  science  B 
and  C ;  if  then  any  one  assumed  that  every  science  is  excel- 
lent, and  also  that  no  science  is,  A  will  be  with  every  B,  and 
with  no  C,  so  that  B  will  be  with  no  C,  no  science  there- 
fore t  is  science.     It  will  be  the  same  also,  if,    ,  _,        .  ,,  . 

.  .,  .  .  ,, '       '     +  Example  (I.) 

having  assumed  that  every  science  is  excellent, 
it  should  be  assumed  that  medicine  is  not  excellent,  for  A  is  with 
every  B,  but  with  no  C,  so  that  a  certain  science  will  not  be 
science,  t  Likewise  if  A  is  with  every  C,  but  with   +  „        ,   ... . 

-d  1    -d    •  •  r*  J-    •  A         •    •  *  Example  (2) 

no  B,  and  B  is  science,  U  medicine,  A  opinion, 
for  assuming  that  no  science  is  opinion,  a  person  would  have 
assumed  a  certain  science  to  be  opinion. §     This1      Exam        . 
however  differs  from  the  former2  in  the  conver- 
sion of  the  terms,  for  before  the  affirmative  was  joined  to  B,3 
but  now  it  is  to  C.  ||    Also  in  a  similar  manner,  if      Thg 
one  premise  is  not  universal,  for  it  is  always  the 
middle  which  is  predicated  negatively  of  the  one  and  affirma- 
tively of  the  other.   Hence  it  happens  that  contradictories  are 

1  Cesare.  2  Camestres. 

3  That  is,  in  Camestres  the  major  of  course  was  affirmative,  the  minor 
negative. 


214  aristotle's  organon.  [book  ii. 

concluded,  yet  not  always,  nor  entirely,  but  when  those  which 
*  i.  e.  the  ex-  are  under  the  middle  *  so  subsist  as  either  to  be 
tremes,  being  the  same,  or  as  a  whole  to  a  part : l  otherwise  it 
middle1  in  2nd  is  impossible,  for  the  propositions  will  by  no  means 
figure.  De  either  contrary  or  contradictory, 

r  .v  .v.-  ^        In  the  third  figure  there  will  never  be  an  af- 

4.  In  the  third  .  •,    °   „  .  .  .  c 

no  affirmative  firmative  syllogism  trom  opposite  propositions,  tor 
is  deduced.  the  reason  alleged  in  the  first  figure ;  but  there 
will  be  a  negative,  both  when  the  terms  are  and  are  not  uni- 
versal. For  let  science  be  B  and  C,  and  medicine  A,  if  then 
a  person  assumes  that  all  medicine  is  science,  and  that  no 
medicine  is  science,  he  would  assume  B  present  with  every  A, 
and  C  with  no  A,  so  that  a  certain  science  will 
+  Example  (4.)   ^  be  gcience.j.     Likewise,  if  the  proposition  A 

B  is  not  taken  as  universal,  for  if  a  certain  medicine  is  science, 
and  again  no  medicine  is  science,  it  results  that  a  certain  sci- 
ence is  not  science.}  But  the  propositions  are 
"  xampe(j-  contrary,  the  terms  being  universally  taken,2  if 
however  one  of  them  is  particular,3  they  are  contradictory. 

We  must  however  understand  that  it  is  possible  thus  to  as- 
sume opposites  as  we  have  said,  that  every  science  is  good, 
and  again,  that  no  science  is  good,  or  that  a  certain  science 
is  not  good,  which  does  not  usually  lie  concealed.  It  is  also 
possible  to  conclude  either  (of  the  opposites),  through  other 
interrogations,  or  as  we  have  observed  in  the 
viii°ch.  i°.°  Topics, §  to  assume  it.  Since  however  the  op- 
5.  opposition  positions  of  affirmations  are  three,  it  results  that 
six-fold.  we  may  taj,e  0pp0S;tes  m  six  Ways,  either  with 

every  and  with  none,  or  with  every  and  not  with  every  indi- 
vidual, or  with  a  certain  and  with  no  one ;  and  to  convert 

1  As  genus  to  species — thus  science  is  related  to  medicine. 

Ex.  4.  No  medicine  is  science 
All  medicine  is  science 
.  • .  A  certain  science  is  not  science. 
A  B 

Ex.  5.  A  certain  medicine  is  not  science. 
A  C 

All  medicine  is  science 

C  B 

.  * .  A  certain  science  is  not  science. 
»  In  Felapton.  3  In  Bokardo. 


CHAP.  XV.  j 


THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS. 


21, 


this  in  the  terms,  thus  A  (may  be)  with  every  B  but  with 
no  C,  or  with  every  C  and  with  no  B,  or  with  the  whole  of 
the  one,  but  not  with  the  whole  of  the  other ;  and  again,  we 
may  convert  this  as  to  the  terms.  It  will  be  the  same  also  in 
the  third  figure,  so  that  it  is  clear  in  how  many  ways  and  in 
what  figures  it  is  possible  for  a  syllogism  to  arise  through  op- 
posite propositions. 

But  it  is  also  manifest  that  we  may  infer  a  true 
conclusion  from  false  premises,  as  we  have  ob- 
served* before,  but  from  opposites  we  cannot,  for 
a  syllogism  always  arises  contrary  to  the  fact,  as 
if  a  thing  is  good,  (the  conclusion  will  be,)  that  it  i>ie  from  such 
is  not  good,  or  if  it  is  an  animal,  that  it  is  not  an  Pr°P°sitions- 
animal,  because  the  syllogism  is  from  contradiction,  and  the 
subject  terms  are  either  the  same,  or  the  one  is  a 
whole,f  but  the  other  a  part.}  It  appears  also 
evident,  that  in  paralogisms l  there  is  nothing  to 
prevent  a  contradiction  of  the  hypothesis  arising, 
as  if  a  thing  is  an  odd  number,  that  it  is  not  odd, 
for  from  opposite  propositions  there  was  a  con- 
trary syllogism ;  if  then  one  assumes  such,  there 
will  be  a  contradiction  of  the  hypothesis.  We  must  under- 
stand, however,  that  we  cannot  so  conclude  contraries  from 
one  syllogism,  as  that  the  conclusion  may  be  that  what  is  not 
good  is  good,  or  any  thing  of  this  kind,  unless  such  a  pro- 
position is  immediately  assumed,2  as  that  every  animal  is 
white  and  not  white,  and  that  man  is  an  animal.3 
But  we  must  either  presume  contradiction,4  as 
that  all  science  is  opinion,5  and  is  not  opinion, 
and  afterwards  assume  that  medicine  is  a  sci- 
ence indeed,  but  is  no  opinion,  just  as  Elenchi6 
are    produced,    or   (conclude)    from    two    syllo- 


*  Vide  this 
t-ook,  chapters 
2,  3,  and  4. 

6.  No  true  con- 
clusion deduei- 


■f  Genus. 
X  Species. 

7.  From  con- 
tradictories a 
contradiction 
to  the  assump- 
tion is  inferred. 


8.  To  infer  con- 
tradiction in 
the  conclusion, 
we  must  have 
contradiction  in 
the  premises. 
(Vide  Whately, 
b.ii.  c.  2  and  3.) 


1  All  reasoning  from  opposites  is  faulty,  because  one  proposition  is 
necessarily  false. 

2  A  proposition  opposed. 

3  The  minor ;  the  conclusion  will  be,  man  is  white  and  not  white. 

4  That  is,  at  firsi    suppose  an  axiom  :ontradictory  of  subsequent  con- 
clusion, e-  g-  all  science  is  opinion. 

5  This  clause  is  omitted  by  Waitz,  it  is  the  conclusion  contradicting 
the  hypothesis. 

6  In  the  '20th  chapter  of  this  book,  an  Elenchus  is  denned  to  be  a  syllo- 
gism of  contradiction,  or  (b.  i.  c.  1,  Soph.  Elun.)  "a  syllogism  with  con- 


216  aristotle's  .  organon.  [book  ii. 

gisms.1  Wherefore,  that  the  things  assumed  should  really  be 
contrary,  is  impossible  in  any  other  way  than  this,  as  was  be- 
fore observed. 

tentiis  syiio-  Chap.    XVI. —  Of  the  "  Petitio  Principii"  or 

gisticis.  (Aver-  Begging  the  Question?  * 

rois.) 

1.  what  the       -po  \ye„  anci  assume  the  original  (question)  con- 

"  petitio  pnn-  °  P  .     .     .  , 

cipii "  is — t6  sists,  (to  take  the  genus  ot  it,)  in  not  demon - 
*}■'?*#  a>Tei<>-  strating  the  proposition,  and  this  happens  in  many 
ways,  whether  a  person  does  not  conclude  at  all,  or  whether 
he  does  so  through  things  more  unknown,  or  equally  unknown, 
or  whether  (he  concludes)  what  is  prior  through  what  is  pos- 
t  vide  Post.  terior  ;  for  demonstration  is  from  things  more 
An.  b.  i.  ch.  2,   creditable  and  prior,  t     Now  of  these  there  is  no 

10   32  ... 

begging  the  question  from  the  beginning,  but  since 
some  things  are  naturally  adapted  to  be  known  through  them- 
selves, and  some  through  other  things,  (for  principles3  are 
+  „     .    .        known  through  themselves,  but  what  are  under 

I  Conclusions.  .  »  ' 

principles!  through  other  things,)  when  a  person 

2.  How  this  fai-  endeavours  to  demonstrate  by  itself  what  cannot  be 
sT/mirfLo^c'  known  by  itself,  then  he  begs  the  original  question, 
p.  331,  et  seq.  '   It  is  possible  however  to  do  this  so  as  immediately 

to  take  the  thing  proposed  for  granted,  and  it  is 

tradiction  of  the  conclusion,"  "  proprie  syllogismus  est  adversarium  re- 
darguens,  confirmando  scil.  quod  illius  sententiae  contradicat."  Aldrich. 
It  is  well  observed  by  Dr.  Hessey,  that  the  iXeytcTiicbv  ti>6vfi)]fia  of  the 
Rhetoric  seems  to  include  the  two  processes,  rj  tig  rb  dSvv.  d-rvayiiiyi)  and 
avWoyig.  Sid  tov  dfivv.,  An.  Pr.  i.  38,  and  to  correspond  to  the  tig  to  advv. 
ayovaa  dnoSei^ig,  An.  Post.  i.  26.  Vide  Hessey's  Tables,  4,  llhet.  ii. 
22,  and  ii.  24. 

1  Proving  affirmation  in  one,  and  negation  in  the  other. 
This  takes  place  when  one  of  the  premises  (whether  true  or  false)  is 
either  plainly  equivalent  to  the  conclusion,  or  depends  on  that  for  its  own 
reception.  The  most  plausible  form  of  this  fallacy  is  arguing  in  a  circle, 
(vide  supra,)  and  the  greater  the  circle,  the  harder  to  detect.  Whately,  b. 
iii.  sect.  4.  Aristotle  enumerates  five  kinds  of  it,  these  however  do  not 
concur  with  those  given  by  Aldrich  in  his  Fallacies  extra  dictionem.  As 
to  the  identity  of  the  syllogism  with  a  petitio  principii,  see  Mansel's  Logic, 
Appendix,  note  D.    Conf.  Top.  8 ;  also  Pacius  upon  this  chap. 

3  These  precede  all  demonstration  :  for  their  relative  position  refer  to 
note  p.  81  ;  also  Meta.  v.  1,  x.  7,  vi.  4,  and  Sir  W.  Hamilton  Reid'a 
Works,  p.  16. 


CHAP.  XVI.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  21" 

also  possible,  that  passing  to  other  things  which  are  naturally 
adapted  to  be  demonstrated  by  that  (which  was  to  be  investi- 
gated), to  demonstrate  by  these  the  original  proposition  ;  as 
if  a  person  should  demonstrate  A  through  B,  and  B  through 
C,  while  C  was  naturally  adapted  to  be  proved  through  A- 
for  it  happens  that  those  who  thus  syllogize,  prove    2  Exam  . 
A  by  itself.     This  they  do,1  who  fancy  that  they   given  of  ma- 
describe  parallel  lines,  for  they  deceive  themselves    thematicians 
by  assuming  such  things  as  they  cannot  demonstrate  unless 
they  are  parallel.     Hence  it  occurs  to  those  who  thus  syllo- 
gize to  say  that  each  thing  is,  if  it  is,  and  thus  every  thine 
will  be  known  through  itself,  which  is  impossible. 
If  then  a  man,  when  it  is  not  proved  that  A  is 
with  C,  and  likewise  with  B,  begs  that  A  may  be 
admitted  present  with  B,  it  is  not  yet  evident  whether  he 
begs  the  original  proposition,  but  that  he  does  not  prove  it  is 
clear,  for  what  is  similarly  doubtful  is  not  the  principle  of 
demonstration.     If  however  B  so  subsists  in  reference  to  C 
as  to  be  the  same,2  or  that  they  are  evidently  convertible,  or 
that  one  is  present  with  the  other,3  then  he  begs   4. 
the  original  question.   For  that  A  is  with  B,  may    #  . 
be  shown  through  them,  if  they  are  converted,   the  minor,  and 
but  now4  this  prevents5  it,  yet  not  the  mode  ;  if  through  c.B 
however  it  should   do   this,*  it   would    produce   5.  +  Beg  the 
what  has  been  mentioned  before,f  and  a  conver-   iuestlon- 
sion  would  be  made  through  three  terms.6     In  like  manner 
if  any  one  should  take  B    to  be  present  with  C,  whilst  it  is 
equally  doubtful  if  he  assumes  A  also  (present  with  C),  he 

1  Those  beg  the  question  who  endeavour  to  show  that  certain  lines  are 
parallel  because  they  never  meet,  for  they  ought  to  prove  that  equi-dis- 
tant  lines  do  not  meet ;  so  that  it  is  tantamount  merely  to  saying  that 
lines  are  equi-distant  because  they  are  equi -distant,  and  they  prove  the 
same  thing  by  the  same,  and  beg  the  question. 

2  The  same  in  reality,  as  a  vestment  and  a  garment.     Taylor. 

3  B  predicated  of  C,  as  genus  of  spec'es. 

*  i.  e.  when  this  is  done,  viz.  B  predicated  thus  of  C. 

5  That  is,  B  being  of  wider  extension  than  A,  prevents  the  demonstrat- 
ing A  of  B  through  C,  though  the  syllogistic  mode  does  not  prevent 
conversion  taking  place,  but  rather  favours  it,  since  it  is  Parbara,  wherein 
alone  a  perfect  circle  is  produced  by  this  kind  of  conversion. 

8  Not  always  really  three,  but  sometimes  one  term  is  assumed  f  ji  two, 
and  therefore  in  one  respect  there  are  three  terms. 


213  aristotle's  organon.  [book  ii. 

does  not  yet  beg  the  question,  but  he  does  not  prove  it.  If 
however  A  and  B  should  be  the  same,  or  should  be  converted, 
or  A  should  follow  B,  he  begs  the  question  from  the  beginning 
for  the  same  reason,  for  what  the  petitio  principii  can  effect 
we  have  shown  before,  viz.  to  demonstrate  a  thing  by  itself 
which  is  not  of  itself  manifest. 

If  then  the  petitio  principii  is  to  prove  by  it- 
may  occur  in  self  what  is  not  of  itself  manifest,  this  is  not  to 
andVrdfiKures  prove,  since  both  what  is  demonstrated  and  that 
but  in  the  case  by  which  the  person  demonstrates  are  alike  du- 
tive^yiiJ^sm  bious,  either  '  because  the  same  things  are  assumed 
by  the  3rd  and  present  with  the  same  thing,  or  the  same  thing 
with  the  same  things  ;2  in  the  middle  figure,  and 
also  in  the  third,  the  original  question  may  be  the  ob- 
jects of  petition,  but  in  the  affirmative  syllogism,  in  the  third 
and  first  figure.3  Negatively  when  the  same  things  are  absent 
from  the  same,  and  both  propositions  are  not  alike,4  (there  is 
the  same  result  also  in  the  middle  figure,)  because  of  the  non- 
conversion  of  the  terms  in  negative  syllogisms.5  A  petitio 
principii  however  occurs  in  demonstrations,  as  to  things  which 
thus  exist  in  truth,  but  in  dialectics  as  to  those  (which  so  sub- 
sist) according  to  opinion. 

1  i.  e.  when  A  and  B  are  the  same,  thus  A  is'  said  to  be  with  C  in  the 
conclusion,  but  B  with  C  in  the  minor,  and  in  Barbara. 

2  i.  e.  when  B  and  C  are  the  same  with  which  in  Barbara  A  is  present, 
the  latter  being  predicated  of  B  in  the  major,  and  of  C  in  the  con- 
clusion. 

3  Because  there  is  no  affirmative  syllogism  in  the  2nd  figure. 

4  A  petitio  principii  can  only  occur  in  an  affirmative  proposition. 

5  i.  e.  the  terms  of  a  negative  proposition,  being  different  in  significa- 
tion, cannot  be  converted,  which  would  be  necessary  if  a  petitio  principii 
could  occur  in  an  affirmative  proposition.  For  whenever  this  fallacy 
occurs  in  the  other  proposition,  the  subject  and  attribute  should  be  iden- 
tical, or  nearly  so.  After  all,  it  must  be  remembered  that  the  Pet.  Prin. 
is  a  material,  and  non-logical,  not  a  formal  fallacy. 


CHAP.  XVII.1  THE   PRIOR  ANALYTICS.  219 


Chap.  XVII. — A  Consideration  of  the  Syllogism,  in  which  it  is 
argued,  that  the  false  does  not  happen — "  an  account  of  £/«'»,'' 
vapa  tovto  ovpfiaivtiv,  to  \ptvfioc.1 

That  the  false  does  not  happen  on  account  of  this    ,  This  h 
(which  we  are  accustomed  to  say  frequently  in   pens  in  a  de- 

\.  \  «      ,    .  n       •  i       j1  duction  to  the 

discussion)  occurs  hrst  in  syllogisms  leading  to   impossible, 
the  impossible,   when  a  person  contradicts  that   T'h\c.h  is, con". 

r  '  r  Ti-  i         tradicted  not  in 

which  was  demonstrated  by  a  deduction  to  the   ostensive  de- 
impossible.  For  neither  will  he  who  does  not  con-   monstratlon- 
tradict  assert  that  it  is  not  (false)  on  this  account,  but  that 
something  false  was  laid  down  before  ;2  nor  in  the  ostensive 
(proof),  since  he  does  not  lay  down  a  contradiction.  Moreover 
when  any  thing  is  ostensively  subverted  through   n  u  e  osten 
A  B  C,*  we  cannot  say  that  a  syllogism  is  pro-   s'veiy  through 
duced  not  on  account  of  what  is  laid  down,  for  we 
then  say  that  is  not  produced  on  account  of  this,  when  this 
being   subverted,   the   syllogism   is   nevertheless   completed, 
which  is  not  the  case  in  ostensive  syllogisms,  since  the  thesis 
being  subverted  the  syllogism  which  belongs  to  it  will  no 
longer  subsist.     It  is  evident  then  that  in  syllogisms  leading 
to  the  impossible,  the  assertion,  "  not  on  account  of  this,"  is 
made,  and  when  the  original  hypothesis  so  subsists  in  refer- 
ence to  the  impossible  as  that  both  when  it  is,  and  when  it  is 
not,  the  impossible  will  nevertheless  occur. 

Hence  the  clearest  mode  of  the  false  not  subsist-   „   _. 

2.   The  per- 

ing  on  account  of  the   hypothesis,  is  when  the  feet  example  ot 
syllogism  leading  to  the  impossible  3  does  not  con-   the  prop,  of 
join  with  the  hypothesis  by  its  media,  as  we  have   which  the 

_  ,  syllo   consists 

observed  in  the  j"  Topics.  For  this  is  to  assume  as   do  not  concur. 
a  cause,  what  is  not  a  cause,  as  if  any  one  wishing    t  sop.  Eien. 
to  show  that  the  diameter  of  a  square  is  incom- 


1  "Non  penes  hoc."  Averr. — "  non  per  hoc."  Waitz.  Confer.  Sop 
Elen.  v.  11,  29,  1 ;  Rhet.  ii.  24;  Whately,  ill.  3  and  4  ;  Hill's  ed.  Aid 
rich,  p.  330. 

*  Viz.  of  the  propositions  anterior  to  the  conclusion.  He  also  who  uses 
an  ostensive  proof,  of  course  does  not  adduce  a  proposition  contradictory 
of  what  he  wishes  to  prove. 

3  Taylor  translates  this  passage  somewhat  differently,  but  I  prefer  the 
rendering  of  Buhle.  Aristotle  joins  the  Sop.  Elen.  with  the  Topics,  be- 
cause the  former  contain  sophistical,  as  the  other  dialectic,  places.— Note 
Julius  Pacius. 


220  aristotle?s  organon.  fBOOK  n. 

mensurate  with  its  side  should  endeavour  to  prove  the  argu- 
ment of  Zeno,*  that  motion  has  no  existence,  and 
*  33P-4Elen' x*  to  this  should  deduce  the  impossible,  for  the  false 
is  by  no  means  whatever  connected  with  what  was 
stated  from  the  first.1  There  is  however  another  mode,  if  the 
impossible  should  be  connected  with  the  hypothesis,  yet  it  does 
not  happen  on  account  of  that,  for  this  may  occur,  whether  we 
assume  the  connexion  up  or  down,  as  if  A  is  placed  present 
with  B,  B  with  C,  and  C  with  D,  but  this  should  be  false, 
that  B  is  with  D.  For  if  A  being  subverted  B  is  neverthe- 
3.  Another  less  with  C,  and  C  with  D,  there  will  not  be 
mode.  the    false    from    the    primary    hypothesis.       Or 

a°-ain,  if  a  person  should  take  the  connexion  upward,  as  if 
2  A  should  be  with  B,  E  with  A,  and  F  with  E, 

but  it  should  be  false  that  F  is  with  A,  for  thus 
there  will  be  no  less  the  impossible,  when  the  primary  hypo- 
thesis is  subverted.     It  is  necessary  however  to 

1.  Necessity  of  .  .        .  .,,  .  .       .  »       ,  ,. 

connecting  the   unite   the  impossible  with  the  terms  (assumed) 
™P,0Sfubl!  from  the  beginninsr,  for  thus  it  will  be  on  account 

with  the  terms  o  e>' 

assumed  from  of  the  hypothesis  ;  f  as  to  a  person  taking  the 
■M.  e?the  im-  connexion  downward,  (it  ought  to  be  connected) 
possible  will  be  with  the  affirmative  term  ;  for  if  it  is  impossible 
that  A  should  be  with  D,  when  A  is  removed 
there  will  no  longer  be  the  false.  But  (the  connexion  being 
assumed)  in  an  upward  direction,  (it  should  be  joined)  with  the 
subject,  for  if  F  cannot  be  with  B,  when  B  is  subverted,  there 
will  no  longer  be  the  impossible,  the  same  also  occurs  when 
the  syllogisms  are  negative. 

It  appears  then  that  if  the  impossible  is  not  connected  with 
the  original  terms,  the  false  does  not  happen  on  account  of 
the  thesis,  or  is  it  that  neither  thus  will  the  false  occur  always 
on  account  of  the  hypothesis  ?  For  if  A  is  placed  present  not 
with  B  but  with  K,  and  K  with  C,  and  this  with  D,  thus  also 
the  impossible  remains ;  and  in  like  manner  when  we  take 
the  terms  in  an  upward  direction,  so  that  since  the  impossible 
happens  whether  this  is  or  this  is  not,  it  will  not  be  on  account 

1  That  the  diameter  of  a  square  is  not  commensurable  with  its  side 
Upon  the  argument  called  Achilles,  which  Zeno  used  to  support  the  lead- 
ing tenet  of  Parrnenides,  viz.  the  unity  of  all  things;  a  sophism  which 
after  all  turns  upon  the  falsity  of  the  major  premise.  See  Plato,  Parm.  128, 
Cousin,  Nouv.  Frag.,  and  Maiisel,  p.  125.   Ar.  Phys.  lib.  vi. 


CHAP.  XVin.  XIX.]    THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS. 


221 


of  the  position.*  Or  if  this  is  not,  the  false  ne- 
vertheless arises ;  it  must  not  be  so  assumed,  as 
if  the  impossible  will  happen  from  something  else 
being  laid  down,  but  when  this  being  subverted, 
the  same  impossible  is  concluded  through  the  re- 
maining propositions,  since  perhaps  there  is  no 
absurdity  in  inferring  the  false  through  several 
hypotheses,  as  that  parallel  lines  meet,1  both  whether  the  in 
ternal  angle  is  greater  than  the  external,  or  whether  a  tri 
angle  has  more  than  two  right  angles. 


•  i.  e.  the  hy- 
pothesis. 

5.  This  not 

to  be  employ- 
ed as  if  a  de- 
duction to 
the  impossible 
arises  from 
other  terms. 


Chap.  XVIII. — Of  false  Reasoning. 

False  reasoning  arises  from  what  is  primarily 

false.      For  every  syllogism  consists  of  two  or 

more  propositions,  if  then  it  consists  of  two,  it  is 

necessary  that  one  or  both  of  these  should  be  false, 

for  there  would  not  be  a  false  syllogism  from  true 

propositions.!     But  if  of  more  than  two,  as  if  C   book>  cnaP- 

(is  proved)  through  A  B,  and  these  through  D  E 

F  G,  some  one  of  the  above2  is  false,  and  on  this  account  the 

reasoning  also,  since  A  and  B  are  concluded  through  them. 

Hence  through  some  one  of  them  the  conclusion  and  the  false 

occur.3 


I.  False  con- 
clusion arises 
from  error  in 
the  primary 
propositions. 

t  Vide  this 


Chap.  XIX. —  Of  the  Prevention  of  a  CatasyllogismA 


To  prevent  a  syllogistical  conclusion  being  ad- 
duced against  us,  we  must  observe  narrowly  when 
(our  opponent)  questions  the  argument5  without 
conclusions,  lest  the  same  thing  should  be  twice 
granted  in  the  propositions,  since  we  know  that 


1.  Rule  to  pre- 
vent the  ad- 
vancement of 
a  catasyllogism 
is  to  watch 
against  the 
same  term 


1  This  is  a  false  conclusion  from  two  false  hypotheses  ;  the  one,  that 
when  a  line  falls  on  two  parallel  lines  the  internal  angle  is  greater  than 
the  external  angle  ;  the  other  is,  if  a  triangle  has  three  angles  greater 
than  two  right  angles. 

2  i.  e.  D  E  F  G. 

3  i.  e.  the  false  conclusion  C.  Vide  Aldrich  and  Huyshe  for  the 
rules  of  syllogism. 

4  Kara<rv\\oyiZioOai  vox  dialcctica,  disputatioDum  et  interrogatiouuin 
laqueis  aliquein  irretire.    VVaitz. 

5  i.  e.  the  propositional  matter. 


222  Aristotle's  organon.  £eook  ti. 

being  twice  ad-  a  syllogism  is  not  produced  without  a  middle,  but 
mitted  in  the  the  middle  is  that  of  which  we  have  frequently 
spoken.  But  in  what  manner  it  is  necessary  to 
observe  the  middle  in  regard  to  each  conclusion,  is  clear  from 
our  knowing  what  kind  of  thing  is  proved  in  each  figure,  and 
this  will  not  escape  us  in  consequence  of  knowing  how  we 
sustain  the  argument.1 

Still  it  is  requisite,  when  we  argue,  that  we 
and  meThod^f  should  endeavour  to  conceal  that  which  we  direct 
masking  our       the  respondent  to  guard  against,2  and  this  will  be 

design  in  hi"-  ° 

gument— two  done,  first,  if  the  conclusions  are  not  pre-syllogized, 
ingyth°iLeffect     Dut  are  unknown  when  necessary  propositions  are 

assumed,  and  again,  if  a  person  does  not  question 
those  things  which  are  proximate,  but  such  as  are  especially 

immediate,*  for  instance,  let  it  be  requisite  to  con- 

*eiysidLogtca.n"  clude  A  of  F>  and  ^t  the  media  be  B  C  D  E ; 
therefore  we  must  question  whether  A  is  with  B, 
and  again,  not  whether  B  is  with  C,  but  whether  D  is  with 
E,  and  afterwards  whether  B  is  with  C,  and  so  of  the  rest. 
If  also  the  syllogism  arises  through  one  middle,  we  must  begin 
with  the  middle,  for  thus  especially  we  may  deceive  the  re- 
spondent. 

Chap.  XX. — Of  the  Elenchus? 

••  The  e,en-  Since  however  we  have  when,  and  from  what  man- 
tio)  is  a  syiio-     ner  of  terminal  subsistence  syllogism  is  produced,  it 

1  We  shall  know  the  principal  conclusion,  as  being  the  subject  matter 
of  our  dispute. 

*  i.  e.  if  we  wish  to  infer  an  indefinite  conclusion,  we  should  secretly 
endeavour  that  our  opponent  may  grant  us  two  propositions,  in  which  the 
middle  is  latent ;  if  however  we  wish  to  infer  a  definite  conclusion,  we 
must  assume  propositions  containing  the  middle  from  which  the  con- 
clusion is  inferred  mediately  and  remotely.  Taylor,  from  whom  the 
above  note  is  chiefly  taken,  appears  to  have  fallen  into  the  same  error  as 
Buhle,  Boeth,  and  some  of  the  older  interpreters,  by  reading  fiiaa  instead 
of  afitaa,  which  I  have  followed  from  Waitz  and  Averrois,  and  which 
the  former  evidently  proves  to  be  the  right  reading.  Vide  Waitz,  torn.  i. 
p.  521 ;  Aver.  vol.  i.  p.  159;  Top.  8.  Immediate  inference  is  that  with 
which  opposition  and  conversion  are  connected;  mediate  pertains  to  in- 
duction and  syllogism. 

3  An  tTri\eipt]fia  admits  of  a  species  of  this,  which  is  called  airoprjfia 
The  original  meaning  of  IXtyxog  is,  as  Dr.  Hessey  observes,  (Table  4,) 
the  refutation  of  an  actual  adversary's  position,  and  so  indirectly  a  con- 


CHAP.  XXI.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS. 


223 


is  also  clear  when  there  will  and  will  not  he  an  gism  of  contra- 

Elenchus.     For  all  things  being  granted,  or  the  an-  duce°"  MchPr°' 

swers  being  arranged  alternately,  for  instance,  the  there  must  be 

one  being  negative  and  the  other  affirmative,  an  elen-  thoughgthe  iat- 

chus  may  be  produced,  since  there  was  a  syllogism  te.r  ™ay  subsist 

J  r  '  .  •,.°,  without  the 

when  the  terms  were  as  well  in  this  as  in  that  former.  (Conf. 
way,  so  that  if  what  is  laid  down  should  be  con-  s°P-Elen-fi-) 
trary  to  the  conclusion,  it  is  necessary  that  an  elenchus  should 
be  produced,  for  an  elenchus  is  a  syllogism  of  contradiction. 
If  however  nothing  is  granted,  it  is  impossible  that  there 
should  be  an  elenchus,  for  there  was  not  a  syllogism  when  all 
the  terms  are  negative,  so  that  there  will  neither  be  an  elen- 
chus, for  if  there  is  an  elenchus,  it  is  necessary  there  should 
be  a  syllogism,  but  if  there  is  a  syllogism,  it  is  not 
necessary  there  should  be  an  elenchus.  Likewise, 
if  nothing  should  be  universally  laid  down  in  the 
answer,*  for  the  determination  of  the  elenchus 
and  of  the  syllogism,  will  be  the  same.1 


*  i.  e.  if  the 
respondent 
should  not  con- 
cede any  uni- 
versal proposi- 
tion. 


Chap.  XXI. — Of  Deception,  as  to  Supposition — Kara    Conf-  Uet*- 

J  .      •     <■*     i       2  lib.  vi.  and  iii., 

TT)V  VTroXrjipiv-  and  de  Animfi, 

iii.  3,  7. 

Sometimes  it  happens,  that  as  we  are  deceived  in    i.  This  kind  of 

the  position  of  the  terms,!  so  also  deception  arises  as   f0e1<deptlon  two" 

to  opinion,  for  example,  if  the  same  thing  happens    +  vide  ch.  33, 

to  be  present  with  many  things  primary,3  and  a 

person    should    be    ignorant    of    one,    and  think    that    it    is 

present  with  nothing,  but  should  know  the  other. 

For   let    A   be    present   with    B    and    with    C, 

per  se,  (that  is,  essentially,)  and  let  these,  in  like  manner,  be 

with  every  D  ;  if  then  somebody  thinks  that  A  is  with  every 

B,  and  this  with  every  D,  but  A  with  no  C,  and   j  Through  b. 

this  with  every   D ;    he  will   have   knowledge  J    *  p 

and  ignorance  §  of  the  same  thing,  ||  as  to  the  samc.^f   n  a. 

firmation  of  our   own;    but,   practically,  the  process  of  meeting  a  real 
or  supposed  opponent,  is  the  same.     Vide  Rhet.  ii.  '22  and  24. 

1  The  reader  will  profitably  read  upon  this  chapter,  Hill's  notice  and 
examples  of  the  Elenchus,  given  at  p.  3"22  of  his  Logic. 

*  See  Hill  and  Whately  on  Fallacies. 

*  So  Waitz;  Buhle,  and  Taylor  read  Trpwrwg;  the  latter  adds,  i.  e. 
"  without  a  medium,"  a  meaning  which  is  evidently  concurred  in  by 
Waitz. 


224  aristotle's  orgaxox.  "book  n. 

2  Again,  if  one  should  be   deceived   about  thosfa 

*  «  waJrw  things  which  are  from  the  same  class,1  *  as  if  A  is 
w<tt.«x«<m.         with  B    but  th;s  w;t]1   q,   an(j  q  w;th  T))   an(i 

should  apprehend  A  to  be  with  every  B,  and  again  with  no 
C,  he  will  at  the  same  time  both  know  and  not  apprehend 
its  presence.  Will  he  then  admit  nothing  else  from  these 
things,  than  that  he  does  not  form  an  opinion  on  what  he 
knows  ?2  for  in  some  way,  he  knows  that  A  is  with  C  through 
t  c  being  a  B,  just  as  the  particular  is  known  in  thef  uni- 
part  of  B.  versal,  so  that  what  he  somehow  knows,  he  ad- 

I  i.  e.  in  the  '  .  .         . '    . 

first  deception,  mits  he  does  not  conceive  at  ail,  which  is  lmpos- 
middhts^nBar-  sible.  In  what,  however,  we  mentioned  before,^ 
bara  and  Ceia-    if  the  middle  is  not  of  the  same  class,  it  is  impos- 

rent,  not  being       ...  •         i     ,i  •,•  t 

subaltern.  sible  to  conceive  both  propositions,  according  to 

Barbara"^01  °f  eacn  °f  the  media,3  as  if  A  were  with  every  B,  § 
H  Major  of  but  with  no  C,||  and  both  these  with  every  D.^f 
irVhe  minor  of  For  it  happens  that  the  major  proposition  assumes 
both-  a  contrary,  either  simply  or  partially,4  for  if  with 

every  thing  with  which  B  is  present  a  person  thinks  A  is  present, 
but  knows  that  B  is  with  D,  he  also  will  know  that  A  is  with  D. 
Hence,  if,  again,  he  thinks  that  A  is  with  nothing  with  which 
C  is,  he  will  not  think  that  A  is  with  any  thing  with  which 
B  is,  but  that  he  who  thinks  that  it  is  with  every  thing  with 
which  B  is,  should  again  think  that  it  is  not  with  something 
with  which  B  is,  is  either  simply  or  partially  contrary.  Thus 
however  it  is  impossible  to  think,  still  nothing  prevents  (our 
assuming)  one  proposition  according  to  each  (mid- 
dle),5 *  or  both  according  to  one,  as  that  A  is  with 
every  B,  and  B  with  D,  and  again,  A  with  no  C.  For  a  de- 
ception of  this  kind  resembles  that  by  which  we  are  deceived 
about  particulars,  as  if  A  is  with  every  B,  but  B  with  every 
C,  A  will  be  with  every  C.6     If  then  a  man  knows  that  A  is 

'  Taylor  says,  "  co-ordinatum  ;  "  Waitz,  "  ex  eadem  serie."  It  is  clear, 
that  subalterns  are  intended. 

2  For  in  the  major  of  Celarent,  he  assumes  no  C  is  A,  whereas  he 
knows,  as  will  be  shown,  that  C  is  A. 

3  That  is,  he  cannot,  at  one  and  the  same  time,  assume  both  the  prop. 
of  Barbara,  and  both  of  Celarent. 

4  i.  e.  by  reason  of  D,  the  subject  of  both  B  and  C. 

5  i.  e.  one  prop,  for  B,  the  other  for  C,  as  every  B  is  A,  no  C  is  A,  the 
minors  not  being  added. 

s  Vide  Post  An.  i.  1  ;  Eth.  Nicom.  b.  vi.  c.  3. 


CHAP.  XXI.]  THE   PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  225 

with  every  thing  with  which  B  is,  he  knows  also  that  it  is 
with  C  ;  still  nothing  prevents  his  being  ignorant  of  the  ex- 
istence of  C,  as  if  A  were  two  right  angles,  B  a  triangle,  and 
C  a  perceptible  triangle.*  For  a  man  may  think  „  Ex  le  (1  s 
that  C  does  not  exist,  knowing  that  every  triangle 
has  two  (equal  to)  right  angles,  hence  he  will  know  and  be 
ignorant  of  the  same  thing  at  once  ;  for  to  know  3  Distinction 
that  every  triangle  has  angles  equal  to  two  right,   between  uni- 

■  •  i  -a  ■  •    .  .«  •  vcrsJil  3.11(1  pflr- 

is  not  a  simple  thing,  j  but  in  one  respect  arises  ticuiar  know- 
from  possessing  universal  science,  in  another,  par-  ^j^'jj  is  „an. 
ticuiar  science.  Thus  therefore  he  knows  by  uni-  ceps  amw- 
versal  science,  that  C  has  angles  equal  to  two  right  guum"  Waitz' 
angles,  but  by  particular  science  he  does  not  know  it,  so  that 
he  will  not  hold  contraries.  In  like  manner  is  the  reasoning  in 
the  Meno,|  that  discipline  is  reminiscence,  for  it  t  Meno,(Piat.) 
never  happens  that  we  have  a  pre-existent  know-   p-  si.  Ritter, 

,     .  „  rr  .  .  i  •  i     •     i         •         r     vol.  n.  p.  293. 

ledge  ol  particulars,  but  together  with  induction,  b    .  „,  „ 

°.  ,  .  n  •         i  •  r.  §   Cf.  Eth.  VI.  4. 

receive  the  science  ot  particulars  as  it  were  by 
recognition  ;  since  some  things  we  immediately  know,  as  (that 
there  are  angles)  equal  to  two  right  angles,  if  we  know  that 
(what  we  see)  is  a  triangle,  and  in  like  manner  as  to  other 
things. 

By  universal  knowledge  then  we  observe  par-   4.  our  observ- 
ticulars,1  but  we  do  not  know  them  by  an  (innate)   ation  of  parti" 

B  A 

Ex.  1 .  Every  triangle  has  angles  equal  to  two  right  angles  (known) 
C  B 

This  is  a  triangle  (unknown) 

m?-    i_  i  ,,    ".     .,,        ,      S  known  by  universal 

.  • .  Ihis  has  angles  equal  to  two  right  angles  j  unknownJ  by  particular 

knowledge.     Vide  Post.  An.  i.  4. 

1  It  would  weary  the  reader,  and  far  exceed  the  limits  to  which,  ne- 
cessarily, we  confine  our  remarks,  to  enter  fully  into  the  analysis  of 
the  distinction  here  drawn.  In  the  Post  An.  i.  6,  the  subject  is  again 
ntered  upon,  but  for  all  necessary  understanding  of  the  matter,  the 
reader  is  referred  to  Sanderson  upon  Certainty,  book  iii.,  and  to  Mansel's 
notes  upon  Syllogism  quoad  Materiam,  artic.  Opinio,  p.  97,  et  seq.  Al- 
though we  have  translated  inroXrjipvs,  supposition,  yet  as  it  approaches 
nearest  to  our  idea  of  logical  judgment,  (see  Trendelenburg  de  Anima,  p. 
469,)  the  latter  term  shows  at  once,  not  only  the  nature,  but  frequently  the 
causes,  of  error,  (An.  Post.  i.  6,  8,)  which  may  be  individual,  that  is,  con- 
nected with  the  person's  own  constitution  of  mind  or  circumstances,  and, 
both  as  to  universals  and  particulars,  partake  much  of  the  character  of 

Q 


e 


226  aristotle's  organon.  [book  ir. 

culaw,  derived  peculiar  knowledge,  hence  we  may  be  deceived 
iedge°ofruni°W  about  them,  yet  not  after  a  contrary  manner,  but 
yersais,  a  pecu-  while  possessing  the  universal,  yet  are  deceived 

lisritv  noticed. 

(Met.  book  vi.  in  the  particular.  It  is  the  same  also  as  to  what 
9.)  Lockers  Ess.  we  have  Sp0ken  of,  for  the  deception  about  the 
vi.  2.  middle  is  not  contrary  to  science  about  syllogism, 

nor  the  opinion  as  to  each  of  the  middles.  Still  nothing  prevents 
one  who  knows  that  A  is  with  the  whole  of  B,  and  this  again 
with  C,  thinking  that  A  is  not  with  C,  as  he  who  knows  that 
every  mule  is  barren,  and  that  this  (animal)  is  a  mule,  may  think 
that  this  is  pregnant ;  for  he  does  not  know  that  A  is  with  C 
5.  a  deception  from  not  at  the  same  time  surveying  each.  Hence 
from  knowing     jt  }s  evident  that  if  he  knows  one  (of  the  proposi- 

one  prop,  and  .  v  r      r 

being  ignorant  tions),  but  is  ignorant  of  the  other,  he  will  be  de- 
ceived as  to  how  the  universal  subsists  with  refer- 
ence to  the  particular  sciences.  For  we  know  nothing  of  those 
things  which  fall  under  the  senses  as  existent  apart  from 
sense,1  not  even  if  we  happen  to  have  perceived  it  before,  un- 
less in  so  far  as  we  possess  universal  and  peculiar  knowledge, 

6  scientific  anc^  no*  m  tna*  we  energize.  For  to  know  is  pre- 
knowiedge  is  dicated  triply,  either  as  to  the  universal  or  to 
tripiyC.ate  tne  peculiar  (knowledge),  or  as  to  energizing,  so 

that  to  be  deceived  is  likewise  in  as  many  ways. 
Nothing  therefore  prevents  a  man  both  knowing  and  being  de- 
«  i.  e.  so  as  not  ceived  about  the  same  thing,  but  not  in  a  con- 
to  noid  a  self-     trary  manner,*  and  this  happens  also  to  him,  who 

either.  What  however  Aristotle  here  means  is,  that  scientific  knowledge, 
or  that  of  particulars,  is  said  of  truths  deduced  from  higher  truths  ;  hence 
to  each  of  these  there  is  a  foundation,  in  universal  knowledge  (vo&v), 
viz.  we  originally  begin  our  speculation  wpon  them,  s£  akrjQwv  /cat  7rpa>raiv, 
or  intuitively  perceived  truths,  though  these  generals  will  not  of  themselves 
suffice  to  prevent  error  in  particulars,  seeing  that  to  each  of  the  last  its 
own  peculiar  study  and  examination  is  appropriately  necessary.  This  is 
fully  borne  out  by  the  relative  meanings  of  iiricTiifiri  and  vovq.  The 
word  "innate"  we  have  inserted  from  Buhle;  by  a  contrary  manner  is 
not  only  meant,  as  Taylor  says,  "not  in  a  manner  contrary  to  science," 
but  without  holding  a  contradictory  opinion,  we  may  know  the  general, 
yet  mistake  the  particular  truth.  (Cf.  Hill's  note  on  Objective  and  Sub- 
jective Certainty.  Leibnitz  de  Stylo  Nizolii.  Sir  W.  Hamilton  Reid's 
Works,  p.  671.) 

1  Vide  de  Anima,  lib.  ii.  5  and  6. — aioQr\oiQ  is  perception  by  the  senses, 
as  vovg  is  the  intellectual  element.  Vide  Eth.  vi.  1  and  12  ;  in  the  lat- 
ter, aioQ.  is  reckoned  intuition. 


CHAP.  XXI.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  22"/ 

knows  each  proposition,  yet  has  not  considered   contradictory 
before ; '  for  thinking  that  a  mule  is  pregnant,  he   °Pin,on- 
has  not  knowledge  in  energy*  nor  again,  on  ac-   *  "™t«i(p- 

„  .     .       to„    ,  it  ■  7e<".     "  Scien- 

count  oi  opinion/  has  he  deception,  contrary  to   tiam  actu." 
knowledge,  since  deception,  contrary  to  universal   >i"tle8"./Vlde 
'knowledge),  is3  syllogism. 

Notwithstanding,  whoever  thinks  that  the  very   7.  From  a  de- 
being  of  good  is  the  very  being  of  evil,  will  ap-   ^nd°a  person 
prehend  that  there  is  the  same  essence  of  good   may  imagine 
and  of  evil ;  for  let  the  essence  of  good  be  A,  and   concurs  with 
the  essence  of  evil  B ;  and  again,  let  the  essence   its  contrary. 
of  good  be  C.     Since  then  he  thinks  that  B  and  C  are  the 
same,  he  will  also  think  that  C  is  B  ;  and  again,  in  a  similar 
manner,  that  B  is  A,  wherefore  that  C  is  A.|      E        le 
Far  just  as  if  it  were  true  that  of  what  C  is  predi- 
cated B  is,  and  of  what  B  is,  A  is ;  it  was  also  true  that  A  is 
predicated  of  C ;  so  too  in  the  case  of  the  verb  "  to  opine." 
In   like  manner,  as  regards  the  verb  "  to  be,"  for  C  and  B 
being  the  same,  and  again,  B  and  A,  C  also  is  the  same  as  A. 
Likewise,  as  regards  to  opine,  is  then  this  necessary,4  if  any 
one  should  grant  the  first  ?   but  perhaps  that  is  false,5  that 
any  one  should  think  that  the  essence  of  good  is  the  essence 
of  evil,  unless  accidentally,6  for  we  may  opine  this  in  many 
ways,  but  we  must  consider  it  better.7 

1  i.  e.  he  has  not  considered  both  propositions  together. 

2  i.  e.  because  he  thinks  the  mule  parturient. 

3  i.  e.  as  Taylor  says,  it  is  a  deceptive  syllogism,  which  proves  no  mule 
barren,  because  the  universals  are  contrary.  The  opinion  proposed  is 
however  particular,  because  it  thinks  this  particular  mule  barren. 

B  A 

Ex.  2.   He  thinks  the  essence  of  evil  is  the  essence  of  good 

C  B 

He  thinks  the  essence  of  good  is  the  essence  of  evil 
C  A 

.  • .  He  thinks  the  essence  of  good  is  the  essence  of  good. 

4  That  one  who  conjointly  considers  both  propositions  should  hold  con- 
trary opinions,  if  a  person  should  state  the  essence  of  good  and  of  evil  to 
be  identical. 

s  Vide  the  opinion  of  Heraclitus,  upon  the  nature  of  contraries;  also 
Met.  books  ix.  and  xiii. 

•  That  is,  what  is  essentially  good,  for  instance,  to  return  a  person's 
property,  may  be  in  a  certain  case  bad,  as  to  give  a  sword  to  a  madman. 

1  In  the  Ethics  and  Metaphysics. 


228  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  n. 


Chap.  XXII. — On  the  Conversion  of  the  Extremes  in  the  first 

Figure. 

1  if  the  terms  When  the  extremes  are  converted,  the  middle 
connected  by  a  must  necessarily  be  converted  with  both.  For  if 
are  converted!  A  is  present  with  C  through  B,  if  it  is  converted, 
the  middle  an(j  q  js  with  whatever  A  is,  B  also  is  converted 
verted  with  with  A,*  and  with  whatever  A  is  present,  B  also 
both-  is  through  the  middle  C,  and  C  is  converted  with 

e  major,     -g  ^  through  the  middle  A.     The  same  will  occur 
with  negatives,  as  if  B  is  with  C,1  but  A  is  not 
with  B,2  neither  will  A  be  with  C,  if  then  B  is  converted  with 
A,  C  also  will  be  converted  with  A.     For  let  B  not  be  with 
A,3  neither  then  will  C  be4  with  A,  since  B  was  with  every 
C,  and  if  C  is  converted  with  B,  (the  latter)  is  also  converted 
with  A ;  for  of  whatever  B  is  predicated,  C  also 
is,  and  if  C  is  converted  with  A,  B  also  is  con- 
verted with  A,  for  with  whatever  B  is  present,  C  also  is,5  but 
3.  Themodeof  C  is  not  present  with  what6  A  is.    This  also  alone 
mTative" f  *io-   DeSms  from  the  conclusion,  (but  the  others  not 
gism,  begins      similarly,)  as  in  the  case  of  an  affirmative  syllo- 
X"sfon,eas0iri     gism.     Again,  if  A  and  B  are  converted,  and  C 
Barbara.  and  D  likewise ;  but  A  or  C  must  necessarily  be 

present  with  every  individual ;  B  and  D  also  will  so  subsist, 
as  that  one  of  them  will  be  present  with  every  individual. 
For  since  B  is  present  with  whatever  A  is,  and  D  with  what- 
ever C  is,  but  A  or  C  with  every  individual,  and  not  both  at 
the  same  time,  it  is  evident  that  B  or  D  is  with  every  indi- 
vidual, and  not  both  of  them  at  the  same  time  ;  for  two  syllo- 
I  omitted  by  gisms  are  conjoined. :j:  Again,  if  A  or  B  is  with 
waitz.  every  individual  and  C  or  D,  but  they  are  not 

2-  present  at  the  same  time,  if  A  and  C  are  converted 

B  also  and  D  are  converted,  since  if  B  is  not  present  with  a 
certain  thing  with  which  D  is,  it  is  evident  that  A  is  present 

1  The  minor  of  Celarent.  2  The  major  of  Celarent. 

3  The  minor  of  Camestres.  4  The  conclusion  of  Camestres. 

s  i.  e.  every  B  is  C,  this  is  the  major  of  Camestres,  inferred  from  the 
conversion  of  the  minor  of  Celarent'. 

•  i.  e.  no  A  is  C,  the  minor  of  Camestres,  taken  from  the  conversion  of 
the  conclusion  of  Celarent. 


CHAV    XXII.]  THE   PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  229 

with  it.  But  if  A  is,  C  also  will  be,  for  they  are  converted, 
so  that  C  and  D  will  be  present  at  the  same  time,  but  this  is 
impossible  ; l  as  if  what  is  unbegotten  is  incorruptible,  and  what 
is  incorruptible  unbegotten,  it  is  necessary  that  what  is  be- 
gotten should  be  corruptible,  and  the  corruptible  begotten. 
But  when  A  is  present  with  the  whole  of  B  and  C,  and  is 
predicated  of  nothing  else,  and  B  also  is  with  every  C,  it  is 
necessary  that  A  and  B  should  be  converted,  as  since  A  is 
predicated  of  B  C  alone,  but  B  itself  is  predicated  both  of  it- 
self and  of  C,  it  is  evident  that  of  those  things  of  which  A  is 
predicated,  of  all  these  B  will  also  be  predicated,  except  of  A 
itself.  Again,  when  A  and  B  are  with  the  whole  of  C,  and 
C  is  converted  with  B,  it  is  necessary  that  A  should  be  with 
every  B,  for  since  A  is  with  every  C,  but  C  with  B  in  conse- 
quence of  reciprocity,  A  will  also  be  with  every  B.  But 
when  of  two  opposites  A  is  preferable  to  B,  and  4  caseofeiec- 
D  to  C  likewise,  if  A  C  are  more  eligible  than  B  tjon  of  oppo- 
D,  A  is  preferable  to  D,  in  like  manner  A  should 
be  followed  and  B  avoided,  since  they  are  opposites,  and  C  (is 
to  be  similarly  avoided)  and  D  (to  be  pursued),  for  these  are 
opposed.  If  then  A  is  similarly  eligible  with  D,  B  also  is  simi- 
larly to  be  avoided  with  C,  each  (opposite)  to  each,  in  like  man- 
ner, what  is  to  be  avoided  to  what  is  to  be  pursued.  Hence  both 
(are  similar)  A  C  with  B  D,  but  because  (the  one  are)  more  (eli- 
gible than  the  other  they)  cannot  be  similarly  (eligible),  for 
(else)  B  D  would  be  similarly  (eligible)  (with  A  C).  5  The  r  t 
If  however  D  is  preferable  to  A,  B  also  is  less  to  be  good  and  less 
avoided  than  C,  for  the  less  is  opposed  to  the  less,  fo  thetesYgood 
and  the  greater  good  and  the  less  evil  are  prefer-  and  greater 
able  to  the  less  good  and  the  greater  evil,  where- 
fore the  whole  B  D  is  preferable  to  A  C.  Now  however 
this  is  not  the  case,  hence  A  is  preferable  to  D,  consequently 
C  is  less  to  be  avoided  than  B.  If  then  every  lover  accord- 
ing to  love  chooses  A,  that  is  to  be  in  such  a  condition  as  to 
be  gratified,  and  C  not  to  be  gratified,  rather  than  be  gratified, 
which  is  D,  and  yet  not  be  in  a  condition  to  be  gratified,  which 
is  B,  it  is  evident  that  A,  i.  e.  to  be  in  a  condition  to  be  gratified, 

1  He  had  before  shown  B  to  be  predicated  of  D  universally,  though  it 
does  not  hence  follow  that  they  are  convertible  unless  D  is  shown  to  be 
predicated  of  B  universally ;  this  is  omitted  for  brevity,  as  the  proof  is  the 
same  as  the  other. 


230  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  n. 

is  preferable  to  being  gratified.1  To  be  loved  then  is  preferable 
according  to  love  to  intercourse,  wherefore  love  is  rather  the 
cause  of  affection  than  of  intercourse,  but  if  it  is  especially 

g  The  desire  (tne  cause)  °f  tnis>  this  also  is  the  end.  Where- 
of the  end,  the  fore  intercourse  either,  in  short,  is  not  or  is  for  the 
pursuit!6  (Eth?  sake  of  affection,  since  the  other  desires  and  arts 
b.  i.  c.  7.)  are  thus  produced.*     How  therefore  terms  sub- 

»   \Vaitz  con-  .  L  .  ......  .. 

eludes  the  sist  as  to  conversion,  also  in  their  being  more  eli- 

chapter  here.      gibie  or  m0re  to  be  avoided,  has  been  shown. 

Chap.  X  XIII. —  Of  Induction.2 

1.  Not  only  di-  We  must  now  show  that  not  only  dialectic  and 
deeicticsyiioa-PO  demonstrative  syllogisms  are  produced  through 
gisms,  hut  also    the  above-named  figures,  but  that  rhetorical  are 

rhetorical,  and         ,  .     .         .  °  .  .  _ 

every  species  of  also,  and  in  snort,  every  kind  ot  demonstration 
arTthrough  the  and  ^y  every  method.  (  For  we  believe  all  things 
above-named      either  through  syllogism  or  from  induction!) 

Induction,  then,  and  the  inductive  syllogism  is  to 
prove  one  extreme  in  the  middle  through  the  other,3  as  if  B  is  the 
middle  of  A  C,  and  we  show  through  C  that  A  is  with  B,  for 

1  This  confirms  the  opinion  of  Plato  in  the  Symposium.  The  demon- 
stration is  thus ;  if  of  four  terms  the  first  is  preferable  to  the  2nd,  and 
the  4th  to  the  third,  but  the  1st  and  3rd  together  preferable  to  the  2nd 
and  4th  together,  then  the  1st  is  preferable  to  the  4th,  hence  to  be  in  a 
condition  adapted  to  be  gratified  is  preferable  to  being  gratified. 

2  Aristotle  attributes  the  discovery  of  induction  and  also  of  definition 
to  Socrates,  but  the  induction  of  the  latter  (who  exhibited  both  dialec- 
tically)  comes  closer  to  the  "  example  "  of  Aristotle.  Vide  Gorgias  460, 
also  Metaph.  xii.  4,  5. 

1  i.  e.  to  prove  the  major  term  of  the  middle  by  the  minor.  The  ex- 
pression e£  iiraywyriQ  ovXk. — used  here,  does  not  (as  Mansel  justly  re- 
marks) denote  the  syllogism  proper,  or  reasoning  from  a  whole  to  its 
parts,  but  comprehends  formal  reasoning  generally,  as  in  Rhet.  ii.  25, 
Enthymem  is  spoken  of  as  including  example.  For  induction  properly 
is  an  inverted  syllogism,  which  argues  from  the  individuals  collected 
to  the  universal  or  whole  class  they  constitute,  whereas  syllogism 
does  just  the  reverse.  Upon  the  various  kinds  of  induction  see  Hill's 
Logic,  229,  where  some  examples  are  given ;  also  Mansel's  Logic, 
Appendix  note  F.  Inasmuch  as  we  seldom  can  enumerate  all  the 
individuals  of  a  class,  we  rarely  meet  with  a  specimen  of  perfect  in- 
duction, but  we  agree  with  Whately  in  believing,  that  the  cause  of 
the  opposition  of  induction  to  syllogism,  arises  entirely  from  the  inac- 
curacy in  the  use  of  the  word.  Vide  Whately,  Log.  b.  iv.  c.  i.  1.  Even 
however  the  distinction  between  perfect  and  imperfect  induction  is  extra- 


CHAP.  XXIII.]  THE    PRIOIl   ANALYTICS. 


231 


thus  we  make  inductions.  Thus  let  A  be  long- 
lived,  B  void  of  bile,  C  every  thing  long-lived,  as 
man,  horse,  mule ;  A  then  *  is  present  with  the 
whole  of  C,  for  every  thing  void  of  bile  is  long- 
lived,  but  Bf  also,  or  that  which  is  void  of  bile, 
is  present  with  every  C,  if  then  C  is  converted 
with  B,|  and  does  not  exceed  the  middle,  it  is 
necessary  that  A  should  be  with  B.  For  it  has 
been  before  shown,1  that  when  any  two  things 
are  present  with  the  same  thing,  and  the  extreme 
is  convertible  with  one  of  them,  that  the  other 
predicate  will  also  be  present  with  that  which  is  converted 
We  must  however  consider  C  as  composed  of  all 
singulars,  for  induction  is  produced  through  §  all. 
A  syllogism  of  this  kind  however  is  of  the  first, 
and  immediate  proposition  ;  for  of  those  which 
have  a  middle,  the  syllogism  is  through  the  mid- 
dle, but  of  those  where  there  is  not  (a  middle)  it  proved  without 
is  by  induction.2  In  some  way  also  induction  is 
opposed  to  syllogism,  for  the  latter  demonstrates 
the  extreme  II  of  the  third  through  the  middle,  but 
the  former  the  extreme  of  the  middle  through  the 
third.  %  To  nature  therefore  the  syllogism  pro- 
duced through  the  middle  is  prior  or  more  known,  but  to  us 
that  by  induction  is  more  evident.3 

logical.  The  reader  may  profitably  consult  on  this  subject  the  Edinburgh 
Review,  No.  115,  p.  '229;  Bacon,  Nov.  Orga.  lib.  2,  Aph.  x. ;  Sir  W. 
Hamilton  lieid's  Works,  p.  712.  The  word  tiraywyri,  or  induction,  is 
clearly  taken  from  the  Socratic  accumulation  of  instances,  serving  as 
antecedents  to  establish  the  requisite  conclusion.  Confer.  Cicero  de  In- 
ventione  i.  32. 

1  In  the  preceding  ch. 

C  A 

Ex.  1.  Every  man,  horse,  mule,  is  long-lived 
B  C 

Whatever  is  void  of  bile  is  man.  horse,  mule 
B  A 

. ' .  Whatever  is  void  of  bile  is  long-lived. 

*  Vide  Aldrich's  Logic  upon  the  second  species  of  demonstration,  v.  5, 
1 ;  also  remarks  made  before  upon  the  use  of  the  terms  mediate  and  im- 
mediate. 

*  Some  things  are  more  known  to  nature,  but  others  more  known  to 
us.  Vide  Post.  An.  i.  1,  2  ;  Pliny,  b.  i.  z.  1  ;  Metaph.  b.  ii.  c.  1.     Com- 


2.  Induction  is 
proving  the 
major  term  of 
the  middle  by 
the  minor. 

*  The  major  of 
the  induction  . 
in  the  3rd 
figure. 

t  The  minor  o/ 
the  induction. 

I  A  reduction 
to  the  1st 
figure. 


§  Example  (1.) 

3.  Induction  is 
occurrent  in 
those  demon- 
strations, 
which  are 


||  i.  e.  the 
major. 

f  The  minor. 


232  aristotle's  organon.  [book  ii 


1.  *<„««««.„«.,  Chap.  XXIV.-O/ Example} 

or  example,  is 

majo'^/the  Example  is  when  the  extreme  is  shown 2  to  be 
middle  by  a  present  with  the  middle  through  something  similar 
bu^gThe111  to  the  third,3  but  it  is  necessary  to  know  that  the 
minor.  middle  is  with  the  third,  and  the  first  with  what 

is  similar.4     For  example,  let  A  be  bad,  B  to  (make  war)  upon 
neighbours,  C   the  Athenians  against  the   Thebans,   D  the 
Thebans  against  the  Phocians.     If  then  we  wish 
,         to  show  that  it  is  bad  to  war  against  the  Thebans, 

*   Example.  ,  •    ° 

we  must  assume  that  it  is  bad  to  war  against 
neighbours,  but  the  demonstration  of  this  is  from  similars,  as 
that  (the  war)  by  the  Thebans  against  the  Phocians  (was  bad). 
Since  then  war  against  neighbours  is  bad,  but  that  against 
the  Thebans  is  against  neighbours,  it  is  evidently  bad  to  war 
against  the  Thebans,  so  that  it  is  evident  that  B  is  with  C, 
and  with  D,  (since  both  are  to  war  against  neighbours,)  and 
that  A  is  with  D,  (for  the  war  against  the  Phocians  was  not 
advantageous  to  the  Thebans,)  but  that  A  is  with  B  will  be 

pare  also  the  whole  chapter  with  Rhet.  b.  i.  c.  2,  b.  ii.  c.  23 ;  and 
Ethics,  Nic.  b.  vi.  c.  3. 

1  Compare  Rhet.  b.  ii.  c.  20,  24,  and  b.  iii.  c.  1 7.  Example  differs 
from  induction,  1st,  in  that  the  latter  proves  the  universal  from  a  complete 
enumeration  of  individuals,  whilst  example  selects  single  cases;  2nd, 
Induction  stops  at  the  universal,  whilst  example  infers  syllogistically  a 
conclusion  regarding  another  individual :  in  fact,  example  includes  an 
imperfect  (therefore  illogical)  induction  and  a  syllogism.  Sometimes  it  is 
called  loosely  reasoning  from  analogy,  but  as  logic  recognises  only  formal 
consequence,  neither  analogy  nor  example  have  any  logical  force.  (Vide 
Mill's  Logic,  b.  iii.  ch.20  ;  also  Mansel,  p.  82.)  The  distinction  is  however 
better  drawn  by  Hill,  p.  243,  comprehending,  1st,  the  antecedent,  which  in 
induction  consists  of  several  singular  cases,  but  in  example  frequently 
of  only  one.  2nd,  the  conclusion,  being  universal  in  induction,  but 
singular  in  example :  he  adds  as  usual  various  examples.  See  also 
Whately,  b.  iv.  ch.  1  and  2.  As  to  the  place  which  irapaStiypa  occupies 
with  regard  to  the  relation  of  the  subject  matter  of  a  premise  to  the  sub- 
ject matter  of  the  conclusion,  in  the  consideration  of  Enthymem,  the  ex- 
cellent Tables  of  Dr.  Hessey,  2,  Div.  1,  and  Table  5,  give  a  complete 
scheme  of  their  position,  also  the  statement  of  the  argument  given  in  the 
text.  It  is  evident,  as  Aristotle  shows,  that  example  consists  of  two 
elements,  a  quasi  inductive  syllogism  apparently  in  Fig.  3,  and  a  deductb« 
syllogism  in  Fig.  1,  so  it  is  assailable  in  each  of  these. 

*  i.  e.  the  major.  3  The  minor. 

*  i.  e.  with  what  is  similar  to  the  minor. 


CHAP.  XXV.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  233 

shown  through  D.     In  the  same  manner  also  if  the  demon- 
stration of  the  middle  as  to  the  extreme  should  be 
through  many  similars,  wherefore  it  is  evident   subs'utTas e 
that  example  is  neither  as  part  to  a  whole,  nor  as   p,art  l,0  part* 

A  *■  J  (air  jutpo? 

whole  to  a  part,  but  as  part  to  part,1  when  both  are   ^p"?  ««p?r.) 

*■  "wherein  it 

under  the  same  thing,2  but  one  is  known.  It  differs  from  in- 
(example)  also  differs  from  induction,  because  the  note  abo'veY*16 
latter  shows  from  all  individuals  that  the  extreme3 
is  present  with  the  middle,  and  does  not  join  the  syllogism  to 
the  extreme,  but  the  former,4  both  joins  it,  and  does  not  de- 
monstrate from  all  (individuals). 

Chap.  XXV. — Of  Abduction.*  1.  'Anaywy^ 

a  syllogism 

Abduction  is  when  it  is  evident  the  first  is  pre-   prem?  certain, 
sent  with  the  middle,0  but  it  is  not  evident  that  and  the  n}™T 

,       .     ,  -iii  i  i     •      •  more  credible 

the  middle  is  with  the  last,  though  it  is  similarly   than  the  con- 
credible,  or  more  so,  than  the  conclusion  ;  more-    clusion- 
over  if  the  media  of  the  last  and  of  the  middle  be  few,  for  it 
by  all  means  happens  that  we  shall  be  nearer  to  knowledge. 
For  instance,  let  A  be  what  may  be  taught,  B   2.  Moreover 
science,  C  justice  ;  that  science  then  may  be  taught  ^proved bythe 
is  clear,  but  not  whether  justice  is  science.     If  interposition 

1  "  Exemplo  utemur  ut  singula  demonstremus  per  singula." — Waitz. 
A  is  a  whole,  B  part  of  A,  C  D  parts  of  B,  when  therefore  example  pro- 
ceeds from  D  to  C,  it  proceeds  from  part  to  part. 

2  As  C  and  D  under  the  same  A,  but  D  more  than  C  is  known  to  be 
under  A. 

3  i.  e.  the  major  A  with  the  middle  B,  and  does  not  join  the  syllogism 
with  the  minor,  in  other  words,  it  does  not  prove  A  of  C. 

4  Example  proves  A  of  C,  and  does  not  demonstrate  from  all  individuals, 
but  only  from  some  of  them,  under  B. 

5  This  term  (anay.)  must  not  be  confounded  when  it  occurs  alone, 
with  the  meaning  it  bears,  in  reference  to  the  impossible,  for  when  it  is 
by  itself,  as  here,  it  signifies  a  syllogism  with  a  major  premise  certain, 
and  a  minor  more  probable,  or  demonstrable,  than  the  conclusion. 
Aldrich  is  so  far  right  in  using  the  word  '"oblique,"  as  applied  to  it, 
(though  utterly  wrong  in  limiting  its  sense  only  to  the  "  ducens  ad  im- 
possible,") in  that  the  word  means"  a  turning  oft',"  from  the  immediate 
point  to  be  proved,  to  something  else  on  which  it  may  depend,  this  is  the 
foundation  of  the  meaning  it  bears  here,  and  the  more  general  acceptation 
of  it  as  a  deduction  per  impossibile.  Syllogistically  it  holds  a  place 
between  the  demonstration  and  the  dialectic  syllogism.  Confer.  Mansel 
and  Hill's  Logic.         6  i.  e.  when  the  major  is  known. 


234  ARISTOTLE'S   ORGANON.  [BOOK    II 

of  few  middle     therefore  B  C  is  equally  or  more  credible  than 
terms.  A  C,1  it  is  abduction,  for  we  are  nearer  know- 

•  Example  (i.)  ^e^Se  because  of  our  assuming  A  C,  not  possess- 
ing science  before.*    Or  again,  if  the  media  of  B 
C  should  be  few,  for  thus  we  are  nearer  knowledge,  as  2  if  D 
should  be  to  be  squared,  E  a  rectilinear  figure,  and  F  a  circle, 
then  if,  of  E  F  there  is  only  one  middle,  for  a 
An.epr.ac.tZ24n    circle  to  become   equal   to  a  rectilinear   figure, 
t  Example  (2.;  through  lunula?,  will  be  a  thing   near  to  know- 
ledge.!    But  when  neither  B  C  is  more  credible 
than  A  C,  nor  the  media  fewer,  I  do  not  call  this  abduction, 
nor  when  B  C  is  immediate,  for  such  a  thing  is  knowledge. 


.   _.  Chap.  XXVI.— Of  Objection.3 

(Instantia,)  a 

proposition        Objection  is  a  proposition  contrary  to  a  propo- 

,iontr?iT"v  to  'i 

proposition,  it     sition,  it  differs  however  from  a  proposition  be- 

1  The  minor  than  the  conclusion. 

B  A 

Ex.  1.  Every  science  may  be  taught. — Known. 

C  [  Equally  or  more  credible  than  the 

All  justice  is  science.  \  conclusion. 

C  A 

.  • .  All  justice  may  be  taught. — Unknown. 

2  As  Taylor  remarks,  Arist.  here  refers  to  the  quadrature  of  the  circle 
by  Hippocrates  of  Chius. 

E  D 

Ex.  2.  Every  rectilinear  figure  may  be  squared. — Known. 

p  v  ( proved  through 

/  'A  A ! 

Every  circle  may  become  a  rectilinear  figure.  )  ?ne  miac}le> 

J  J  °         \i.  e.  per  lunulas. 

F  D        |  This   is    proved   through    many 

Every  circle  may  be  squared.  \  media. 

3  We  assail  an  adversary  either  by  bringing  an  ivaraaiq  to  show  his 
conclusion  is  not  proved,  or  by  disproving  his  conclusion,  by  an  avrtavX- 
Xoyia/xog,  (objection  to  consequent,)  i.  e.  by  proving  its  contradictory  by 
means  of  a  new  middle  term.  Now  "Evorao-tc  may  either  be  material, 
or  objection  to  antecedent,  or  formal  objection  to  consequent.  If  material, 
it  may  be  either  Ik  tclvtov,  Ik  tov  tvavriov,  sk  tov  u/ioiov  Ik  jcpio-£a>e,  or 
«k  tov  Kara  do£av :  (see  by  this  ch.)  the  relative  position  of  which  the 
reader  will  find  admirably  laid  down  in  Dr.  Hessey's  Schema  Rhetorica, 
wherefrom  this  note  is  chiefly  taken.  The  present  ch.  causes  us  chiefly 
to  notice  the  "Ei>o-racrtc  Ik  ravrov,  and  this  may  be  either  KaOoXov,  or 
Kara  yt'ipoQ.      In  proving  the  first  we  assume  as  a  new  middle,  a  term 


CHAP.  XXVI.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  235 

ca  ase  objection  may  be  partial,  but  proposition   differs  from . 
cannot  be  so   at  all,  or  not  in   universal   syllo-   proposition  in 
gisms.  Objection  indeed  is  advanced  in  two  ways,   l  at  U  maybe 

more  extensive,  and  icaSoXod,  as  compared  with  the  subject  of  the  original 
irpoTamg ;  in  proving  the  ever.  Kara  juspoc,  we  assume  as  a  new  middle, 
a  term  less  extensive  than  the  subject  of  the  original  7rp6ruo-ic.  Now  A 
may  be  assailed  by  proving  its  contrary,  or  contradictory,  in  Fig.  1,  or  its 
contradictory  in  Fig.  3.  E  may  be  assailed  by  proving  its  contrary  (or 
contradictory)  in  Fig.  1,  or  its  contradictory  in  Fig.  3.  Lastly,  an  affirma- 
tive proposition  (but  not  a  negative)  may  be  assailed  by  an  Enstatic 
Enthymem,  in  Fig.  2,  but  Arist.  objects  to  do  so.  Conf.  upon  this  ch., 
Julius  Pacius ;  Whately  on  the  Nature  and  Fallacy  of  Objections  ;  Anal. 
Post.  i.  12  ;  Rhet.  ii.  26  ;  Waitz,  p.  535,  in  loc.  Hermogenes,  in  his  trea- 
tise upon  Invention,  does  not  consider  objection  in  the  same  respect  as 
Arist.  The  apparent  discrepancy  between  this  chap,  and  the  account  of 
objection  in  the  Rhetoric  is  noticed  by  Dr.  Hessey,  Table  5. 

Ex.  1.  Proposition. 

A  B 

There  is  one  science  of  contraries. 

Objection. 
A  C 

There  is  not  one  science  of  opposites 

B  C 

Contraries  are  opposites 

A  B 

. '  .    There  is  not  one  science  of  contraries. 

Ex.  2.  Proposition. 

A  B 

There  is  one  science  of  contraries. 

Objection. 
A  C 

There  is  not  one  science  of  the  known,  and  of  the  unkncvn 

O  B 

The  known  and  the  unknown  are  contraries 

A  B 

There  is  not  one  science  of  contraries. 

Ex.  3.  Proposition. 

A  B 

.  • .  There  is  not  one  science  of  contraries. 

Objection. 
A  C 

There  is  one  science  of  opposites 

B  C 

Contraries  are  opposites 

A  B 

.  * .    There  is  one  scien  w  of  contraries. 


236 


ARISTOTLE  S    ORGAXON. 


[book  n. 


either  xa06\ou 
or  £7t<  Mtpor. 


atives  and 
negatives. 

2.  Method  of 
alleging  the 

t  Celarent. 
X  Felapton. 


and  by  two  figures  ;  in  two  ways,  because  every 
objection  is  either  universal  or  particular,  and  by 
two  figures,  because  they  are  used  opposite  to  the  proposition, 
*  i.  e.  affirm-  and  opposites  *  are  concluded  in  the  first  and  third 
figure  alone.  When  then  a  person  requires  it  to 
be  admitted  that  any  thing  is  present  with  every 
individual,  we  object  either  that  it  is  with  none, 
or  that  it  is  not  with  a  certain  one,  and  of  these, 
the  being  present  with  none,  (is  shown)  by  the 
first  figure,"f  but  that  it  is  not  with  a  certain  one 
by  the  last.|  For  instance,  let  A  be  "there  is  one 
science,  and  B  contraries ;"  when  therefore  a  person  advances 
that  there  is  one  science  of  contraries,  it  is  objected  either 
that  there  is  not  the  same  science  of  opposites,  altogether, 
but  contraries  are  opposites,  so  that  there  is  the 
§  Example  (i.)   grsj.  figUre  .{j  or  t]ia^  there  is  not  one  science  of 

the  known  and  of  the  unknown,  and  this  is  the 
third  figure,||  for  of  C,  that  is,  of  the  known,  and 
of  the  unknown,  it  is  true  that  they  are  contraries, 
but  that  there  is  one  science  of  them  is  false.^f 
Again,  in  like  manner  in  a  negative  proposition,  for  if  any  one 
asserts  that  there  is  not  one  science  of  contraries,  we  say  either 
that  there  is  the  same  science  of  all  opposites,  or  that  there  is 
of  certain  contraries,  as  of  the  salubrious,  and  of  the  noxious  ; 
that  there  is  therefore  (one  science)  of  all  things 
is  by  the  first  figure,*  but  that  there  is  of  certain 
by  the  third.f  In  short,  in  all  (disputations)  it  is 
necessary  that  he  who  universally  objects  should 
apply  a  contradiction  of  the  propositions  to  the 
universal,^  as  if  some  one  should  assert  that  there 
is  not  the  same  science  of  all  contraries,  (the  ob- 
jector) should  say,  that  there  is  one  of  opposites.  For  thus 
it  is  necessary  that  there  should  be  the  first  figure, 
since  the  middle  becomes  an  universal  to   that 


Felapton. 


IT  Example  (2.) 


*  Barbara. 

t  Darapti. 

t  Example  (3.) 
3.  Rule  for  the 

KaOoXov 
evtrraiTi?. 


4.  And  for  that 


Proposition  the  same. 

Objection. 
A  C 

There  is  one  science  of  the  salubrious  and  noxious 

C  B 

The  salubrious  and  noxious  are  contraries 
A  B 

•  •t    There  is  one  science  of  certain  contraries. 


CHAP.  XXVI.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS  237 

(which  was  proposed)  at  first,  but  he  who  objects  nv0£pe'"  Vide 

in  part  (must  contradict)  that  which  is  universal,  §  §  Subject. 
of  which  the  proposition  is  stated,  as  that  there  is  not  the  same 

science  of  the  known,  and  the  unknown,  for  the  m  _         . 

contraries  are  universal  with  reference,  to  these.*  attributed  to 

The  third  figure  is  also  produced,  for  what  is  par-  uhnek^°™™d 

ticularly  assumed  is  the  middle,  for  instance,  the  universal  to 

known  and  the  unknown  ;  as  from  what  we  may  pa 

infer  a  contrary  syllojnstically,  from  the  same  we  en-  5- ' Objection 

j     j        o  *^„ .  adduced  in  the 

deavour  to  urge  objections.  Wherefore  we  adduce  first  and  third 

then  (objections)  from  these  figures  only,f  for  in  fieures  alone- 

these  alone  opposite  syllogisms  are  constructed,  +  Hence  ^  the 

since  we  cannot  conclude  affirmatively  through  the  prop,  is  nega- 

middle  figure.1     Moreover,  even  if2  it  were  (pos-  tlon'toit cannot 

sible),   yet  the  (objection),  in  the  middle   figure  Je  proper  in  the 

,lJ         .  /  •  t  \  •/»    2nd  figure  since 

would  require  more  (extensive  discussion),  as  it  the  objection 
anyone  should  not  admit  A  to  be  present  with  B,  ought  t0  affirm- 
because  C  is  not  consequent  to  it,  (B).  For  this  is  manifest 
through  other  propositions,  the  objection  however  must  not 
be  diverted  to  other  things,  but  should  forthwith  have  the 
other  proposition  apparent,3  wherefore  also  from  this  figure 
alone  there  is  not  a  sign.4 

We  must  consider  also  other  objections,  as  those    .   _..   „ 

i>  t         ■     -i  6-  Objections 

adduced  from  the  contrary,  from  the  similar,  and  of  other  kinds 
from  what  is  according  to  opinion,5  also  whether  vWeenot!  i?d' 
it  is  possible  to  assume  a  particular  objection  from  ?upra ;  Rhet. 
the  first,  or  a  negative  from  the  middle  figure. 

1  In  self-defence  upon  this  "  vexed  place,"  I  am  obliged  to  quote  the 
note  of  Julius  Pacius  as  corroborative  of  the  sense  I  have  given  in  the 
text ;  Waitz  however  in  most  obscure  phraseology  comes,  as  Dr.  Hessey 
remarks,  to  the  same  point.  The  following  is  from  Pacius  :  "  Aristoteles 
loquens  de  universali  objectione  inquit  hoc  simpliciter  ;  id  est,  generaliter 
in  omnibus  disputationibus  obtinere,  ut  necesse  sit,  eum  qui  universaliter 
objicit,  id  est,  affert  objectionem  universalem  dirigat  contradictionem 
propositorum,  id  est,  suam  objectionem,  qure  opponitur  proposition!  ad- 
versarii ;  dirigat  (inquam)  ad  universale,  id  est  in  ea  objectione  sumat 
terminum  universalem,  qui  attribuatur,  subjecto  propositionis,  ut  in 
exemplo  antea  dato,  sumebamus  hunc  terminum,  dvrtKtifitva  qui  est 
universalis,  et  attribuitur  subjecto  propositionis,  id  est  ivavrloiq."  (Vide 
Julius  Pacius  in  h.  1. ;  also  Waitz,  p.  536,  An.  Pr.) 

2  i.  e.  when  the  prop,  is  affirmative.         3  i.  e.  the  prop,  understood. 

*  See  the  following  ch. 

*  Examples  of  all  these  are  given  in  Table  v.,  Hessey's  Schema  Rhet. 


238  aristotle's  organon.  [book  ii. 


Chap.  XXVII. —  Of  Likeliliood,  Sign,  and  Enthymeme.1 

1.  E«cjt— con-       Likelihood  and  sign,  however,  are  not  the 
sentaneum  ar-   samej  kut  tiie  iikeiy  js  a  probable  proposition  for 

1  For  writers  upon  the  subjects  of  this  chapter  we  may  refer  to  the  com- 
mentary of  Julius  Pacius,  (Excerpta,)  and  Crakanthorpii  Logica,  lib.  v., 
both  annexed  to  the  Schema  Rhetorica  of  Dr.  Hessey ;  No.  115,  in  the 
Edinburgh  Review,  attributed  to  Sir  W.  Hamilton;  Mansel's  Logic,  Ap- 
pendix, note  E. ;  Whately's  Rhetoric  and  Buckley's  note,  Bohn's  edi- 
tion of  the  Rhetoric,  book  i.  chap.  2.  The  older  writers  upon  it  are 
Rodolphus  Agricola,  1485,  Phrissemius,  1523,  J.  Pacius,  Scaynus,  1599, 
and  Majoragius,  (1572).     We  now  proceed  to  the  words  themselves. 

The  term  Ei'icdc,  we  prefer,  with  Sir  W.  Hamilton,  to  interpret  "  likeli- 
hood" to  the  other  senses  given  by  commentators  we  have  named  in  the 
margin,  since  the  former  approaches  nearer  to  its  Aristotelian  definition 
as  a  proposition  stating  a  general  probability.  This  indeed  is  a  propo- 
sition nearly,  though  not  quite,  universal,  and  when  employed  in  an 
Enthymeme,  will  form  the  major  premise  of  a  syllogism  such  as  the 
following : 

Most  men  who  envy,  hate. 

This  man  envies  : 

Therefore  this  man  (probably)  hates. 

Aristotle  limits  it  to  contingent  matter,  and  its  relation  to  the  conclusion 
is  that  of  an  universal  to  a  particular. 

2t}(ielov,  on  the  other  hand,  in  a  propositional  sense,  is  a,  fact  which  is 
known  to  be  an  indication,  more  or  less  certain,  of  the  truth  of  some  fur- 
ther statement,  whether  of  a  single  fact  or  of  a  general  belief.  We  say  in  a 
propositional  sense,  for  sometimes  Ei'koc,  ffrjfielov,  and  tikjx^'iov,  are  used 
for  the  Enthymemes  drawn  from  each;  it  is,  in  fact,  a  singular  proposition 
employed  relatively  to  some  other  proposition  which  may  be  inferred  from 
it,  and  will  form  one  premise  of  a  syllogism,  which  may  be  in  either  of 
these  figures  which  Aristotle  discusses,  having  respect  in  this  division  to 
the  extent  of  the  so-called  middle  term,  as  compared  with  the  other  two 
terms.  In  the  first  and  second  figures  it  is  the  minor  premise,  in  the 
third  it  seems  more  naturally  to  belong  to  the  major.  Whately  con- 
siders the  tiKoc  (or  Sioti)  of  Aristotle  to  be  an  a  priori  argument,  which 
may  be  employed  to  account  for  the  fact,  whereas  the  oqfisiov  (or  on) 
could  not  be  so  employed ;  he  has  however  glanced  at  this  point  but 
generally.  Aristotle  tells  us  that  we  may  either  class  rtK/iripiov,  as  he 
does  in  the  Rhet.  c.  2,  as  a  species  of  otj/jLiiov,  or  contradistinguish  two 
crr/fiita— in  necessary  matter  as  in  the  relation  of  a  particular  to  an  uni- 
versal, or  of  an  universal  to  a  particular,  and  class  the  reicfiripiov  as  a 
species  under  a  genus.  By  a  reference  to  Dr.  Hessey's  Tables  the  exact 
position  of  each  in  the  enthymematic  system  may  be  clearly  perceived  : 
we  may  merely  add  that,  as  propositions,  it  is  no  where  stated  that  a/cef 
and  Sq/itiof  may  not  be  combined  in  the  same  syllogism,  and  that  much 
of  apparent  contradiction  between  the  places  in  the  Analytics  and  liheto- 


CHAP.  XXVII.]  THE    PRIOR   ANALYTICS.  23c> 

what  men  know  to  have  generally  happened  or  gumentum, 

not,  or  to  be  or  not  to  be  ;    this  is  a  likelihood,  BuhieandTay. 

for  instance,  that  the  envious  hate,  or  that  lovers  ie"'ande"  ver!'- 

love  :  but  a  sign  seems  to  be  a  demonstrative  pro-  similltudo," 

i     i  i        p  i  i-i       Averrois, 

position,  necessary  or   probable,  tor  that  which  waitz;"proba- 

when  it  exists  a  thing  is,  or  which  when  it  has  "'ifkeUhood!" 

happened,  before  or  after,  a  thing  has  happened,  Sir  w.  Hamii- 

this  is   a   sign  of   a  thing  happening  or  being,  babie  'proposi- 

Now  an  Enthymeme  is  a  syllogism  from  likelihoods  |s°"dem^n""ray. 

or  signs,  but  a  sign  is  assumed  triply  in  as  many  tive  proposi- 

ways  as  the  middle  in  the  figures,  for  it  is  either  cessary  orrpn>- 

as  in  the  first,  or  as  in  the  middle,  or  as  in  the  bable- .  Enthy- 

mcnic  is  3.  svl~ 

third,  as  to  show  that  a  woman  is  pregnant  be-   logism  drawn 
cause  she  has  milk  is  from  the  first  figure,  for  the   from  either  oi 

ric  may  be  solved  by  a  careful  study  of  the  tabular  view  given  by  the 
Doctor,  of  the  consideration  of  these  elements  of  Enthymeme,  first  as 
propositions,  next  as  terms. 

In  regard  to  Enthymeme,  it  is  no  wonder  that  difficulties  should  not 
vanish,  when  even  the  abandonment  of  the  word  artXijg,  ejected  as  a 
gloss  by  Pacius,  and  discountenanced  by  the  best  MSS.  of  the  old  Latin 
version,  is  still  clung  to  by  some  authors.  Enthymeme  is  composed  of 
tiKora,  or  arjfitla,  and  without  circumscribing  our  notion  of  it  within  the 
limits  absurdly  laid  down  of  its  etymology  by  Aldrich,  we  may  conceive  it 
in  a  general  sense  as  comprehending  iriaTiiq  of  every  kind  ;  and  at  other 
times  limited  to  a  special  kind  of  syllogism  designated  rhetorical.  Vari- 
ous senses  have  been  attributed  to  it  by  Cicero,  Quintilian,  and  others,  but 
Aristotle  in  general  describes  it  as  one  sort  of  argument  on  moral  matters 
distinguished  carefully  as  to  its  principle  from  example,  a  collateral  sort  of 
argument.  In  the  words  of  Sir  W.  Hamilton,  "  Enthymeme  is  distin- 
guished from  pure  syllogism  as  a  reasoning  of  peculiar  matter  from  signs 
and  likelihoods  ;"  whether  therefore  a  premise  of  it  be  suppressed  or 
not,  an  argument  agreeing  with  this  description  is  an  Enthymeme.  The 
words  cnroSuKTiKi)  dvayicaia  i]  tvSo^og,  applied  to  aijfitlnv  as  a  7rporafftc, 
do  not  relate  to  the  modal  character  of  the  proposition  in  itself,  but  to  its 
logical  validity  when  the  other  premise  is  added,  without  which  addition 
expressed  or  understood,  there  is  no  Enthymeme  at  all.  Lastly,  Zimtlov 
is  called  a  demonstrative  proposition,  because  it  professes  to  enunciate 
what  is  absolutely  true,  i.  e.  what  Aristotle  calls  necessary,  (Rhet.  i.  c.  2,) 
the  latter  word  being  used  in  two  senses,  1st,  of  a  premise  which  states  a 
fact,  2nd,  of  a  consequence  which  is  logically  unassailable. 

B  A 

■^-x.  1.  Whatever  woman  has  milk  is  pregnant 
C  B 

This  woman  has  milk 
C  A 

.    .  This  worr.an  is  pregnant. 


240  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  il 

these,  cf.         middle  is  to  have  milk.     Let  A,  be  to  be  preg- 

Soph."<Ed.coL  nant'  B  t0   have  milk>  C  a  woman.*     But  that 

292  and  ii99.  wise  men  are  worth y,  for  Pittacus  is  a  worthy 

sumediripty",  man,  is  through  the  last  figure,  let  A  be  worthy, 

according  to  £  wise  men,  C  Pittacus.     It  is  true  then  A  and 

the  number  of     ^,  ,.  »        ,      -  „.  , 

figures.  B  are  predicated  ot  L,  except  that  they  do  not  as- 

*  Example  (lu  sert  tne  one !  because  they  know  it,  but  the  other 
(a  paralogism.)  they  assume.f  But  that  a  woman  is  pregnant 
because  she  is  pale,  would  be  through  the  middle  figure,  for 
since  paleness  is  a  consequence  of  pregnancy,  and  also  attends 
this  woman,  they  fancy  it  proved  that  she  is  pregnant.  Let 
t  Example  (3.)  A  be  paleness,  to  be  pregnant  B,  a  woman  C.J 
3.  if  one  prop,   jf   then  one    proposition  should  be  enunciated, 

be  enunciated,  .  ,     *■       \  ,  „  ' 

there  is  only  a  there  is  only  a  sign,  but  it  the  other  also  be 
Slgn-  assumed,  there  is  a  syllogism,  as  for  instance  that 

Pittacus  is  liberal,  for  the  ambitious  are  liberal,  and  Pittacus 
is  ambitious,  or  again,  that  the  wise  are  good,  for  Pittacus  is 
good  and  also  wise.     Thus  therefore  syllogisms  are  produced, 

except  indeed  that  the  one  in  the  first  figure  is  in- 
ube^ru^is'irf-  controvertible  if  it  be  true,  (for  it  is  universal,) 
controvertible  Dut  that  through  the  last  is  controvertible  though 
but  notSso  in"  the  conclusion  should  be  true,  because  the  syllo- 
the  last  or  2nd    jrjsm  js  not  universal  nor  to  the  purpose,  for  if 

Pittacus  is  worthy,  it  is  not  necessary  that  on  this 
account  other  wise  men  also  should  be  worthy.  But  that 
which  is  by  the  middle  figure  is  always  and  altogether  con- 
§  i.  e.  when  trovertible,  for  there  is  never  a  syllogism,  when 
ammPremises     tne  terms  tnus  subsist, §  for  it  is  not  necessary,  if 

1  Viz.  "  That  Pittacus  is  a  wise  man,"  but  they  assume  the  other,  viz. 
"  That  Pittacus  is  a  worthy  man." 

C  A 

Ex.  2.  Pittacus  is  a  worthy  man 
C  B 

Pittacus  is  a  wise  man 
B  A 

.  *  .  Wise  are  worthy  men. 

B  A 

Ex.  3    Whatever  woman  is  pregnant  is  pale 
C  A 

This  woman  is  pale 
C  B 

.    ,  This  woman  is  pregnant. 


CHAP.  XXVII.]  THE   PRIOR    4.NALTTICS.  241 

she  who  is  pregnant  be  pale,  and  this  woman  be  »  Bekker  and 
pale,  that  this  woman  should  be  pregnant ;  what  t^i  ^bum" 
is  true  therefore  will  be  in  all  the  figures,*  but  and  Avemris, ' 
they  have  the  above-named  differences.  "xiix*™. 

Either  therefore  the  sign  must  be  thus  divided, 
but  of  these  the  middle  must  be  assumed  as  the l    (indipium,°'a 
proof  positive,  (for  the  proof  positive  they  say  is   syllogism  in 
that  which  produces  knowledge,  but  the  middle  is   (cf.  Quintfuan," 
especially  a  thing  of  this2  kind,)  or  we  must  call   8ib,v- c-  9|  see- 
those  from  the3  extremes,  signs,  but  what  is  from 
the  middle  a  proof  positive,  for  that  is  most  probable,  and  for 
the  most  part  true,  which  is  through   the  first  figure.     We 
may  however  form  a  judgment  of  the  disposition   6   B  the  ex_ 
by  the  body,  if  a  person  grants  that  whatever  pas-   ample  of  phy- 
sions  are  natural,  change  at  once  the  body  and   to^shows "' 
the  soul,4  since  perhaps  one  who  has  learned  music   tna*  ^sns  »- 

i  ill-  i     •  i  •       pecially  proba- 

nas  changed  his  soul  in  some  respect,  but  this   bie  belong  to 
passion  is  not.  of  those  which  are  natural  to  us,    the  lst  fisure- 
but  such  as  angers  and  desires,  which  belong  to  natural  emo- 
tions.     If  therefore  this  should  be  granted,  and  one  thing 
should  be  a  sign  of  one  (passion),  and  we  are  able  to  lay  hold  of 
the  peculiar  passion  and  sign  of  each  genus,  we  shall  be  able 

1  The  TtKfiijpiov  is  a  arifiiiov  in  fig.  1,  necessarily  conclusive,  (vide 
Rhet.  i.  c.  2,)  derived  by  Arist.  from  rsK/xap,  a  boundary.  The  argument 
Sid  TtKjii)oiov  is  logical,  but  rarely  occurs,  since  its  advancement  settles 
the  question.  He  speaks  of  "  the  middle,  "&c,  as  referring  to  the  first  figure, 
in  which  the  middle  term  obtains  the  middle  place.  TtK/xtjoia  can  only 
be  refuted  by  assailing  the  premises. 

2  Cf.  Waitz,  Tom.  i.  p.  538.  Biese,  i.  227,  also  ch.  14,  book  i.  Anal. 
Post. 

3  Which  are  referred  to  the  second  or  third  figure;  "quae  extrema 
sunt  (ut  utrobique  subjecti  aut  utrobique  predicati  locum  habeant,")  ea 
signa  diccnda  sunt;  quod  autem  e  medio  (sumtum  est)  ut  partim  sub- 
jecti, partim  prredicati  vicem  gerat  indicium  dicendum  est.     Buhle. 

4  Cf.  Arist.  Physio.  Eth.  ii.  c.  1,  and  5.  Buhle,  Anal.  i.  ch.  v.  Dan. 
iii.  19.     Gen.  xxxi.  2. 

" My  grief  lies  all  within ; 

And  those  external  manners  of  laments 

Are  merely  shadows  to  the  unseen  grief 

That  swells  with  silence  in  my  tortured  soul. 

There  lies  the  substance." —  Shaks.  Hichd.  II. 

The  same  sentiment  is  met  with  in  our  dramatists  passim.  The  acqui- 
sition of  knowledge  of  course  changes  the  soul ;  since,  to  take  a  high 
view,  it  is  the  first  human  element  of  all  reLgiou. 

h. 


242  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  11. 

r  The  first  to  conjecture  from  nature.  For  if  a  peculiar  pas- 
physiognomic  sion  is  inherent  in  a  certain  individual  genus,  as 
fhat°nhaturaiS  fortitude  in  lions,  it  is  necessary  also  that  there 
passionchanges  should  be  a  certain  sign,  for  it  is  supposed  that 

at  one  time  the      ,  .  ,        ,      ,  ,  i<  ,,  .  ..,  , 

body  and  soul,  they  (the  body  and  soul)  sympathize  with  each 

Uihere2isdoneat  otner»  and  let  this  be  the  having  great  extremi- 

sjgnof  one  pas-  ties,  which  also  is  contingent  to  other,  not  whole, 

that'the  proper  genera.1     For  the  sign  is  thus  peculiar,  because 

passion  of  each  ^he  passion  is  a  peculiarity  of  the  whole  genus, 

species  of  am-  f  i»«-i»-i_i  0  ° 

mai  may  be  and  is  not  the  peculiarity  or  it  alone/  as  we  are 
known.  accustomed  to  say.    The  same  (sign)  then  will  also 

be  inherent  in  another  genus,  and  man  will  be  brave,  and  some 
other  animal,  it  will  then  possess  that  sign,3  for  there  was 
one  (sign)  of  one  (passion).  If  then  these  things  are  so,  and 
we  can  collect  such  signs  in  those  animals,  which  have  one 
peculiar  passion  alone,  but  each  (passion)  has  its  (own)  sign, 
since  it  is  necessary  that  it  should  have  one,  we  may  be  able 
to  conjecture  the  nature  from  the  bodily  frame.  But  if  the 
whole  genus  have  two  peculiarities,  as  a  lion  has  fortitude  and 
liberality,  how  shall  we  know  which  of  those  signs  that  are 
peculiarly  consequent  is  the  sign,  if  either  (passion)  ?  Shall 
we  say  that  we  may  know  this,  if  both  are  inherent  in  some- 
thing else,  but  not  wholly,4  and  in  what  each  is  not  inherent 

1  Other  species,  he  means,  also  have  this  sign,  but  it  is  not  possessed 
by  every  individual  in  the  species. 

2  That  is,  though  it  may  even  happen  to  every  individual,  it  does  not 
happen  to  that  genus  alone.  This  mere  sketch  presents  the  outlines, 
in  comparative  anatomy,  of  the  strongest  evidence  upon  which  modern 
phrenologists  can  rest  their  claim  to  credence ;  it  must  be  remembered 
however  that  the  whole  case  falls,  if  the  identification  of  the  peculiar 
mark  with  the  passion  is  not  fully  proved.  Hi-s  further  question,  of  how 
we  are  to  apportion  each  passion  to  its  own  mark,  when  many  are  pre- 
sent in  one  genus,  seems  unanswerable : — yet  we  have  presumed  even  to 
measure  the  prominence  which  marks  each  passion,  (if  it  does  mark  it,) 
and  to  set  one  over  against  the  other,  e.  g.  benevolence  against  destruct- 
iveness,  almost  to  a  hair's  breadth  ! 

'  Viz.  great  extremities. 

4  i.  e.  If  both  passions  and  both  signs  are  inherent  in  another  genus  of 
animals,  yet  so  as  not  both  to  be  inherent  in  all  the  individuals  of  that 
genus ;  for  instance,  both  courage  and  liberality,  and  their  signs,  are  in 
horses  as  well  as  in  lions,  but  not  in  all  horses,  for  some  are  brave  and 
not  liberal,  others  liberal  and  not  brave. 

Ex.  4.  Whatever  has  great  extremities  is  brave 
Every  lion  has  great  extremities 
. ' .  Every  lion  is  brave. 


CHAP.  XXVII.]  THE    PRIOR    ANALYTICS.  243 

wholly,  when  they  have  the  one,  they  have  not  the  other  ;  for 
if  a  (lion)  is  brave,  but  not  generous,  but  has   ,  .  e  great 
this  *  from  two  signs,  it  is  evident  that  in  a  lion   extremities. 
also  this  is  the  sign  of  fortitude.     But  to  form  a      §  Whateyer 
judgment  of  the  natural  disposition  by  the  bodily   is  inferred  in 
frame,  is,  for  this  reason,  in  the  first  figure,  be-   ^J^?nc\ £ 
cause   the   middle   reciprocates  with  the   major   ut  figure. 
term,  but  exceeds  the  third,  and  does  not  recipro- 
cate with  it ;  as  for  instance,  let  fortitude  be  A,  great  ex- 
tremities B,   and  C  a  lion.     Wherefore  B  is  present  with 
every   individual   with    which    C    is,    but   with      ^  ^  ^^ 
others*  also,  and  A  is  with  every  individual  of  D*„J^i 
that  with  which  B  is  present,  and  with  no  more,    "  man." 
but  is  converted,  for  if  it  were  not,  there  would    (  ExampIe  (4.} 
not  be  one  sign  of  one  (passion).f 

Whatever  has  great  extremities  is  brave 
Some  man  has  great  extremities 
.  •  .  Some  man  is  brave. 


R   1 


244  aristotle's  organon.  [book 


THE  POSTERIOR  ANALYTICS. 

BOOK  I. 

Chap.  I. —  Upon  the  Nature  of  Demonstration. 

All  doctrine,  and  all  intellectual  discipline,1  arise 
tic  discipline  from  pre-existent  knowledge.  Now  this  is  evi- 
from°prevSous  dent,  if  we  survey  them  all,  for  both  mathematical 
knowledge,  sciences  are  obtained  in  this  manner,  and  also 
twofold  re"  each  of  the  other  arts.  It  is  the  same  also  with 
spect.    (Cf.       arguments,   as  well  those  which  result  through 

Mag.  Moral. lib,  .  .  . 

i.  is,  and  Eth.   syllogisms,  as   those  which   are  formed  through 
^u2dej  jlb' v<  c"   induction,    for  both   teach  through   things    pre- 
viously known,  the  one  assuming  as  if  from  those 
who  understood  them,2  the  other*  demonstrat- 
ing the  universal  by  that  which  is  evident  as  to  the  singular. 
Likewise  also  do  rhetoricians  persuade,  for  they  do  so  either 
through   examples,  which    is  induction,   or   through  enthy- 
+  vide  Prior      menis,  which  is  syllogism,  j"3    It  is  necessary  how- 
Anai.  b.  ii.  c.     ever  to  possess  previous  knowledge  in  a  twofold 
respect ;  for  with  some  things  we  must  pre-sup- 
pose  that  they  are,  but  with  others  we  must  understand  what 
that  is  which  is  spoken  of;    and  with  others  both  must  be 

1  Doctrine  and  discipline  are  the  same  in  reality,  but  differ  in  relation, 
being  called  "  doctrine  "  when  applied  to  teaching,  and  "  discipline  "  as 
pertaining  to  learning.  Taylor  defines  Aiavoia,  that  power  of  the  soul 
which  reasons  scientifically,  deriving  the  principles  of  its  reasoning  from 
intellect :  and  these  principles  are  axioms  and  definitions.  Comp.  Poetic, 
ch.  6,  where  the  word  is  applied  to  a  certain  part  of  tragedy.  Ethics,  b. 
vi.  c.  2.  Waitz  notices  the  similarity  between  the  commencement  of  this 
ch.  and  the  opening  ch.  of  the  Ethics.  For  the  principle  stated,  consult 
Hill's  Logic,  p.  137,  and  for  the  word,  see  Biese,  i.  p.  89. 

2  That  is,  syllogisms  contain  propositions,  assumed  to  be  known  either 
by  demonstration  or  per  se. 

3  Vid.  lthet.  b.  i.  ch.  2.  It  was  shown  (b.  ii.  ch.  2  4,  Anal.  Pri.)  that 
example  is  reduced  to  a  syllogism  in  the  1st  figure,  the  major  prop,  of 
which  is  proved  by  an  imperfect  deduction ;  wherefore  as  the  whole 
force  of  th«  example  consists  in  that  induction,  it  is  not  undeservedly  said 
to  be  a  certain  induction.     Tay.or. 


C:iAP.  I.]  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  245 

known,  as  for  instance,  (we  must  pre-assume,)  that  of  every- 
thing it  is  true  to  affirm  or  deny  that  it  is,  but  of  a  triangle, 
that  it  signifies  so  and  so,  and  of  the  monad  (we  must  know) 
both,  viz.  what  it  signifies  and  that  it  is,  for  each  of  these  is 
not  manifest  to  us  in  a  similar  manner.1  It  is  possible  how 
ever  to  know  from  knowing  some  things  previously,2  and  re- 
ceiving the  knowledge  of  others  at  the  same  time,  as  of  things 
which  are  contained  under  universals,  and  of  which  a  man 
possesses  knowledge.3  For  he  knew  before  that  every  tri- 
angle has  angles  equal  to  two  right  angles,  but  that  this  which 
is  in  a  semi-circle  is  a  triangle,  he  knew  by  induction  at  the 
same  time.  For  of  some  things  knowledge  is  acquired  after 
this  manner,  nor  is  the  extreme  known  through  the  middle, 
as  such  things  as  are  singulars,  and  are  not  predicated  of  any 
subject.  Perhaps  however  we  must  confess  that  we  possess 
knowledge  after  a  certain  manner  before  induction  or  the  as- 
sumption of  a  syllogism,  but  in  another  manner  not.4  For 
what  a  man  is  ignorant  about  its  existence  at  all,  how  could 
he  know  at  all  that  it  has  two  right  angles  ?  But  2.  what  we 
it  is  evident  that  he  thus  knows  because  he  knows  aUylnoTgener- 
the  universal,  but  singly  he  does  not  know  it.    aiiywemay 

,      .         -11        -iii        i_  •   i_    ■       not  know  sin- 
Still  if  this  be  not  admitted,  the  doubt  which  is   giy,  although 

mentioned  in  the  Meno*  will  occur,  either  he  will  ^j^6  same 

learn  nothing,  or  those  things  which  he  knows,5   *  Meno,  Piato- 

1  Quae  antequam  disciplina  ipsa  quaecunque  nobis  tradatur,  cognoscere 
debemus  on  tariv,  axiomata  sunt,  quae  vero  cognoscere  debemus  n  to 
Xiyofitvov  tan,  definitiones  sunt :  unde  fit  ut  disciplinam  ipsam  quarn- 
cunque,  praecede  redebeant,  axiomata  et  definitiones.— Nam  etsi  definitio 
rei  naturam  non  patefaciat,  tamen  quam  vim  habeat  nomen  quo  res  signi- 
ficetur  exponit,  ut  etiam  definitio  nominalis,  quae  dicitur  utilitatem 
quandam  habeat.  Waitz.  See  also  Meditationes  de  cognitione  Veritatis 
et  Ideis :  Leibnitz  Opera,  p.  80,  ed.  Erdmann. 

2  i.  e.  to  prove  the  principal  conclusion,  from  certain  propositions 
being  proved,  pro-syllogistically. 

3  Learning  them  not  from  antecedent  knowledge  nor  pro-syllogistically, 
but  immediately,  just  as  sensibles  are  known  by  the  senses.  Taylor. 
Compare  also  Ethics,  b.  vi.  ch.  3,  and  Whately's  Logic. 

4  i.  e.  the  conclusion  may  be  known  by  universal,  yet  it  cannot  be  by 
proper  or  peculiar  knowledge  ;  for  instance,  in  the  case  below  he  knows 
that  this  triangle  has  angles  equal  to  two  right,  because  he  knows  this  to 
be  the  case  universally  of  a  triangle,  but  he  does  not  know  it  singly,  ab- 
solutely, and  perfectly  by  proper  knowledge. 

*  The  passage  in  the  Meno  of  Plato  is  that  commencing  icai  nva  roonot 


246  Aristotle's  organon.  lbook  i. 

nis  Opera,  Bek-  for  he  must  not  say,  as  some  endeavour  to  solve 
!vrp  32' tom'  tne  doubt,  "  Do  you  know  that  every  duad  is  an 
even  number  or  not?"  for  since  if  some  one  says 
that  he  does,  they  would  bring  forward  a  certain  duad  which 
he  did  not  think  existed,  as  therefore  not  even ;  and  they 
solve  the  ambiguity,  not  by  saying  that  he  knew  every  duad 
to  be  even,  but  that  he  was  ignorant  as  to  what  they  know  is 
a  duad.  Nevertheless  they  know  that  of  which  they  possess 
and  have  received  the  demonstration,  but  they  have  received 
it  not  of  every  thing  which  they  know  to  be  a  triangle  or  a 
number,  but  of  every  number  and  triangle  singly,  for  no  pro- 
position is  assumed  of  such  a  kind  as  the  number  which  you 
know,  or  the  rectilinear  figure  which  you  know,  but  univers- 
ally. Still  there  is  nothing  (I  think)  to  prevent  a  man  who 
learns,  in  a  certain  respect  knowing  and  in  a  certain  respect 
being  ignorant,1  for  it  is  absurd,  not  that  he  should  in  some 
way  know  what  he  learns,  but  that  he  should  thus  know  it,  as 
he  does  when  he  learns  it,  and  in  the  same  manner. 

Chap.  II. — Of  Knowledge,  and  Demonstration,  and  its  Elements. 

*  Soph.  Eienc.  We  think  that  we  know  each  thing  singly,  (and 
xi.  l.Metap.  not  in  a  sophistical  manner,*  according  to  acci- 
,  '  .'    ...         dent,)  when  we  think  that  we  know  the  cause  on 

1.  scientific  '  „      .  .   .  .  .         .  ... 

knowledge  is      account  oi  which  a  thing  is,  that  it  is  the  cause  of 

wheSnSwed'know  tliat   tning>   and   tnat  the  hatter  cannot   subsist 

the  necessary  otherwise  ;  wherefore  it  is  evident  that  knowledge 

tween  aching  is  a  thing  of  this  kind,  for  both  those  who  do  not, 

Definition118?'  anc^  *nose  wno  do  know,  fancy,  the  former,  that 

Demonstration,  they  in  this  manner  possess  knowledge,  but  those 

vl.1^^)11105'  wno  know,  possess  it  in  reality,  so  that  it  is  im- 
possible that  a  thing  of  which  there  is  know- 

Z,r\ri\aiiQ.  The  doubt  (air6pr)pa)  is,  that  if  we  can  learn  nothing,  there- 
fore that  nothing  is  to  be  investigated,  since  what  we  know  we  need  not 
investigate,  and  it  is  vain  to  search  after  what  we  know  not,  since  not 
knowing  the  object  of  our  search,  we  shall  be  ignorant  of  it,  even  when 
found.  Socrates  solves  this  (\vti)  by  declaring  that  to  discover  and  to 
learn,  are  nothing  else  than  to  remember,  because  the  soul,  being  im- 
mortal, formerly  knew  every  thing,  of  which  knowledge,  becoming  ob- 
livious by  being  merged  in  the  body,  she  endeavours  to  recall  knowledge 
to  memory  by  investigation. 

1  Knowing  by  universal,  being  ignorant  by  proper  knowledge. 


CHAP.  II.]  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  247 

le<lge  simply  should  subsist  ic  any  other  way.1      Whether 
therefore  there  is  any  other  mode  of  knowing  we  shall  tell 
hereafter,  but  we  say  also  that  we  obtain  knowledge  through 
demonstration,  but  I  call  demonstration  a  scien-   ^  gyiiog  qui 
tific  *  syllogism,  and  I  mean  by  scientific  that  ac-    scire  facit. 
cording  to  which,  from  our  possessing  it,  we  know. 
If  then  to  know  is  what  we  have  laid  down,  it  is   LSt™' 
necessary  that  demonstrative  science  should  be   demonstrative 
from  things  true,  first,  immediate,  more  known 
than,  prior  to,  and  the  causes  of  the  conclusion,  for  thus  there 
will  be  the  appropriate  first  principles  of  whatever  is  demon- 
strated.2    Now  syllogism  will  subsist  even  without  these,  but 
demonstration  will  not,  since  it  will  not  produce 
knowledge.     It  is  necessary  then  that  they  should 
be  true,  since  we  cannot  know  that  which  does  not  subsist,  for 
instance,  that  the  diameter  of  a  square  is  commensurate  with 
its  side.     But  it  must  be  from  things  first  and 
indemonstrable,  or  otherwise  a  man  will  not  know   demonstrable" 
them,  because  he  does  not  possess  the  demonstra- 
tion of  them,3  for  to  know  those  things  of  which  there  is  de- 
monstration not  accidentally  is  to  possess  demon- 
stration.     But  they  must  be  causes,  and   more  the^ndusfon 
known,  and  prior  ;  causes  indeed,  because  we  then 
know  scientifically  when  we  know  the  cause  ;  and  prior,  since 
they  are  causes ;  previously  known   also,  not  only  according 

1  True  science  requires,  1st,  that  the  cause  of  a  thing  be  known,  i.  e. 
that  the  middle  term  be  the  cause  of  the  conclusion ;  2nd,  that  the 
cause  be  compared  with  the  effect,  so  that  we  know  it  to  be  the  cause  of 
the  conclusion ;  3rd,  that  we  know  the  conclusion  to  subsist  thus  neces- 
sarily, and  that  it  cannot  subsist  otherwise.  Taylor.  Comp.  Rhet.  i.  c.  7. 
Magna  Moralia,  i.  c.  34.  Metap.  i.  1,  and  10,  3,  and  7.  Cause  and  apxq 
must  not  be  confounded,  since  the  cause  precedes  the  apx*i  ;  vide  Buck- 
ley's note  in  Bonn's  edition  of  the  Rhetoric  quoted  above. 

2  Vide  Hill's  Logic,  page  289,  also  Mansel,  p.  104,  et  seq. ;  in  the  ap- 
pendix note  H.  of  the  latter's  work,  the  reader  will  find  the  statement  of 
the  nature  of  demonstrative  syllogism  fully  set  forth.  The  words  first 
and  immediate,  signify  that  they  are  not  demonstrable  by  a  middle  term 
from  any  higher  truth.  The  demonstration,  "  propter  quid  sit  per  causam 
non  primam,"  would  only  form  a  subordinate  portion  of  a  complex  de- 
monstration. Vide  Wall's  Log.  lib.  iii.  cap.  22.  As  post  demonstrations 
depend  upon  those  prior,  therefore  all  are  said  to  be  from  things  first. 

3  Either  they  would  be  unknown  or  not  be  principles,  because  they 
might  be  demonstrated  by  other  things  prior  to  them,  ad  infinitum.  Vide 
Whately's  Logic,  b3ok  iv. 


248  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

to  the  other  mode  by  understanding  (what  they 
more  known,  in   signify),  but  by  knowing  that  they  are.1     More- 

spect  f°ld  re      over  tney  are  Prlor  and  more  known  in  two  ways, 

for  what  is  prior  in  nature,  is  not  the  same  as  that 
which  is  prior  in  regard  to  us,  nor  what  is  more  known  (simply) 
the  same  as  what  is  more  known  to  us.  Now  I  call  things 
prior  and  more  known  to  us,  those  which  are  nearer  to  sense, 
and  things  prior  and  more  known  simply,  those  which  are 

more  remote  from  sense ;  and  those  things  are 
sense.'     m        most  remote  *  which  are  especially  universal,2  and 

those  nearest  which  are  singular,  and  these  are 
mutually  opposed.     That  again  is  from  things  first,  which  is 

from  peculiar  principles,3  and  I  mean  by  first,  the 

5.  Immediate.  r,  .  r,        r.     '.    .       ,  ,  J.      .    '        „ 

same  thing  as  the  principle,  but  the  principle  of 
demonstration  is  an  immediate  proposition,  and  that  is  imme- 
diate to  which  there  is  no  other  prior.     Now  a 
of  p^opo"i?«o°n.    proposition  is  one  part  of  enunciation,  one  of  one,4 
dialectic  indeed,  which  similarly  assumes  either 
(part  of  contradiction),  but  demonstrative   which  definitely 
(assumes)  that  one  (part)  is  true.     Enunciation  is  either  part 
of  contradiction,  and  contradiction  is  an  opposi- 
Categories.        tionf  which  has  no  medium  in  respect  to  itself. 
But  that  part  of  contradiction  (which  declares) 

1  Principles  are  prior  in  a  two-fold  respect,  they  cause  a  thing  to  be, 
and  also  cause  the  same  to  be  known.  Taylor.  Comp.  Anal.  Post.  i. 
24.  The  inquiry  into  the  definition  of  a  thing  is  identical  with  that  of  its 
cause,  with  the  difference  that  the  cause  of  attributes  is  to  be  sought  in 
their  subject,  but  in  the  case  of  substances  per  se  the  cause  must  be 
sought  in  themselves  only.     Cf.  Metap.  v.  1,  2  ;  x.  7,  2. 

2  Aristotle  here  intimates  his  concurrence  with  the  Platonic  theory,  that 
the  soul  contains  in  itself  essentially  the  "  universal,"  or  true  principle 
of  demonstration  ;  vide  the  Commentary  of  Proclus  on  the  Parmenides 
of  Plato,  in  which  he  exhibits  the  priority  of  universals  to  singulars,  and 
the  method  of  their  reception  by  the  diancetic  faculty.  Cf.  also  Ritter 
and  Cousin  upon  the  Old  Academy.  Arist.  Ethics,  b.  vi.  c.  11,  and 
Metap.  books  i.  iv.  vi.  and  xii.  (Leip.  ed.)  If  demonstration  be  from 
universals  prior  by  nature,  it  follows,  according  to  Aristotle,  that  it  is 
alone  from  forms  essentially  inherent  in  the  soul,  since  abstract  forms 
are  not  naturally  prior,  because  they  are  universals  of  a  posterior 
origin. 

3  That  principles  ought  to  be  peculiar  to  the  science,  and  to  what  is  to 
be  demonstrated,  he  shows,  ch.  vii.  and  ix. 

4  One  enunciation  signifies  one  thing  of  one.  Vide  ch.  8,  on  Inter- 
pretation. 


CHAP.  II.]  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  249 

something,  of  somewhat,  is  affirmation,  and  that  (which  signi- 
fies) something  from  somewhat  is  negation.*     Of  *  Ch  6  on  In_ 
an  immediate  syllogistic  principle,  I  call  that  the   terpretation. 
thesis,  which  it  is  not  possible  to  demonstrate,  nor  the^if  Tons?- °f 
is  it  necessary  that  he  should  possess  it,  who  in-   dered  by  Pa- 
tends  to  learn  any  thing  ;  but  what  he  who  intends   a^synmymous 
to  learn  any  thing  must  necessarily  possess,  that   with  «w««- 
I  call  an  axiom,1  for  there  are  certain  things  of  5-  0f  axiom- 
this  kind,   and  in   denominating  these,   we   are   accustomed 
generally  to  use  this  name.     But  of  thesis,  that  which  re- 
ceives either  part  of  contradiction,  as  for  instance,  I  mean 
that  a  certain  thing  is,  or  that  it  is  not,  is  hypo- 
thesis, but  that  which  is  without  this,  is  definition.   ^;s0f  hyPothe' 
For  definition  is  a  thesis,  since  the  arithmetician 
lays  down  unity  to  be  that  which  is  indivisible,  according  to 
quantity,  yet  it  is  not  hypothesis,  since  what  unity  is,  and 
that  unity  is,  are  not  the  same  thing. 

Notwithstanding,  since  we  must  believe  in  and  know  a  thing 
from  possessing  such  a  syllogism  as  we  call  demonstration,  and 
this  is,  because  these  are  so,  of  which  syllogism  consists — it 
is  necessary  not  only  to  have  a  previous  knowledge  of  the 
first,  or  all,  or  some  things,  but  that  they  should  be  more  known, 
for  that  on  account  of  which  any  thing  exists,  always  exists  itself 
in  a  greater  degree  ;  for  example,  that  on  account  of  which  we 
love  is  itself  more  beloved.  Hence  if  we  know  and  believe 
on  account  of  things  first,  we  also  know  and  believe  those 
first  things  in  a  greater  degree,  because  through  them  (we 
know  and  believe)  things  posterior.  A  man  however  cannot 
believe  more  than  what  he  knows,  those  things  which  he  does 
not  know,  nor  with  respect  to  which  he  is  better  disposed 

1  Axioms  are  common,  according  to  Aristotle,  to  several  classes,  but 
in  the  case  of  a  single  science  need  only  be  assumed  to  an  extent  com- 
mensurate with  the  object-matter  of  that  science.  As  Mansel  well  ob- 
serves, the  places  in  which  the  axioms  are  mentioned  in  connexion  with 
demonstration,  have  never  been  satisfactorily  explained  on  the  usual 
scholastic  interpretation.  I  entirely  agree  with  him,  that  the  supposition 
that  axioms  are  virtually,  but  not  actually,  employed  in  demonstration, 
and  the  distinction  drawn  between  immediate  propositions  and  axioms, 
are  equally  unfounded  ;  in  fact  it  subverts  Aristotle's  own  expression. 
Vide  Mansel's  Logic,  App.  66.  Compare  also  Zabarella  in  I.  An.  Post. 
Cont.  57,  58.  Crakanthorpe,  Logic,  lib.  iv.  c  1.  Aquinas  Opusc.  48,  de 
Sy'lo.  Dem.  cap.  6. 


250  aristotle's  organon.  [book  t. 

than  if  he  knew.1  This  however  will  happen,  unless  some 
one  should  previously  know  of  those  who  give  credence  through 
demonstration,  since  it  is  more  necessary  to  believe  either  in 
all  or  in  certain  first  principles,  than  in  the  conclu- 
sity  ofknow?ng  sion.  It  is  not  only  however  requisite  that  he  who 
principles  and  js  to  possess  knowledge  through  demonstration, 
in  order  to  pos-  should  know  in  a  greater  degree  first  principles, 
demo'nltrarion7  and  believe  rather  in  them  than  in  the  thing  de- 
monstrated, but  also  that  nothing  else  should  be 
more  credible  or  more  known  to  him  than  the  opposites  of  the 
principles,  from  which  a  syllogism  of  contra-deception  may 
consist,  since  it  behoves  him  who  possesses  knowledge  singly 
to  be  unchangeable.2 

Chap.  III. — Refutation  of  certain  opinions  as  to  Science  and 
Demonstration. 

i   Refutatio       ^0  some'  because  it  is  necessary  that  first  things 
of  those  who      should  be  known,  science  does  not  appear  to  exist, 

e'nce'o^cfenct  but  to  others  to  exist  indeed,  yet  (they  think) 

there  are  demonstrations  of  all  things,  neither  of 

which  opinions  is  true  or  necessary.3    For  those  who  suppose 

1  By  being  better  disposed,  Aristotle,  who  is  here  speaking  of  demon- 
strative knowledge,  means  the  intuitive  apprehension  of  intellect.  Cf. 
Waitz  and  Biese  in  loc. 

2  That  is,  free  from  lapsing  into  error,  which  he  would  fall  into  by  not 
knowing  opposites,  since  he  might  believe  that  the  opposites  to  true  prin- 
ciples are  true.  For  the  better  elucidation  of  the  above  chapter,  the  fol- 
lowing table  of  the  principles  of  science  is  given : 

'ApxaL 

A 

Koivai  (t£  wv)  "iSiai  (irtpi  o) 

a%iti>fiara  Q'eouq 

Constituting  the  original 
premises  from  which  de- 
monstration proceeds. 


<    "~- ; — I- 

Opiff/lOl  VTTOVEOtlQ 

Definitions — real,  of  Assumptions  of  the 

the  subjects — nominal,  existence  of  the 

of  the  attributes.  subjects  as  necessary 

to  their  definition. 
3  The  argument  is  as  follows  :  there  are,  or  are  not,  certain  irpaira ;  if 
there  are  not,  but  we  admit  a  process  ad  infinitum,  there  is  no  science, 
since   the  latter   ultimate^  depends   on   certain  irpwra  :   if  there  are 


CHAP.  III.]  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  2.51 

that  knowledge  does  not  subsist  at  all,  these  thir.k  that  we  are 
to  proceed  to  infinity  as  if  we  may  not  know  things  subse- 
quent by  things  prior,  of  which  there  are  no  first,  reasoning 
rightly,  since  it  is  impossible  to  penetrate  infinites.1  And 
if  (they  say)  we  are  to  stop,  and  there  are  principles,  these 
are  unknown,  since  there  is  no  demonstration  of  them,  which 
alone  they  say  is  to  know  scientifically  ;  but  if  it  is  not  possible 
to  know  first  things,  neither  can  we  know  either  simply  or 
properly  things  which  result  from  these,  but  by  hypothesis, 
if  these  exist.  Others  however  assent  with  re-  2.  Aisoofthose 
spect  to  knowledge,  for  (they  assert)  that  it  is   who  declare  all 

,        ,  ,,        °  .  ,  *  ',.  things  capable 

only  through  demonstration,  but  that  nothing  pre-  of  demonstra- 
vents  there  being  a  demonstration  of  all  things,  tlon' 
for  demonstration  may  be  effected  in  a  circle,  and  (things  be 
proved)  from  each  other.  We  on  the  contrary  assert,  that 
neither  is  all  science  demonstrative,  but  that  the  science  of 
things  immediate  is  indemonstrable.  And  this  is  evidently 
necessary,  for  if  it  is  requisite  to  know  things  prior,  and  from 
which  demonstration  subsists,  but  some  time  or  other  there  is 
a  stand  made  at  things  immediate,  these  must  of  necessity  be 
indemonstrable.     This  therefore  we  thus  assert,    .  _,.   . .    , 

.  i  •  *  1  That  is,  de- 

and  we  say  that  there  is  not  only  science,*  but   monstrative 
also  a  certain  principle  of  science,  by  which  we   science- 
know  terms.2    But  that  it  is  impossible  to  demon-    jj-  We  cannot. 

.  .  .  f  .  demonstrate  in 

strate  in  a  circle  simply  is  evident,  since  demon-   a  circle  things 

"  firsts  "  on  the  other  hand,  still  there  is  no  science,  for  the  latter  being 
from  things  prior,  there  can  be  nothing  prior  to  "  firsts." 

1  They  are  right  in  saying  we  cannot  know  things  posterior  through 
the  prior,  unless  the  progress  of  investigation  stop  at  certain  "  firsts ; " 
they  are  wrong  in  asserting  that  these  firsts  cannot  be  known.  Cf.  Phy- 
sics, lib.  i.  and  iii. 

2  A  certain  knowledge  antecedent  to  demonstrative  science.  The  word 
opoi,  here,  Pacius  mistakes  for  "  simple  terms;"  it  signifies  rather,  as  St. 
Hilaire  observes,  "  les  propositions  immediates,"  i.  e.  axioms.  The  fol- 
lowing is  the  interpretation  by  Ammonius  of  this  place.  The  principle 
of  science  is  intellect,  not  our  intellect,  but  that  which  is  divine  and 
above  us ;  but  terms  are  intelligible  and  divine  forms,  which  axe  called 
terms  in  consequence  of  being  the  boundaries  of  all  things.  For  as  mul- 
titude originates  from  the  monad,  and  is  dissolved  into  the  monad,  and 
tens  are  the  boundaries  of  hundreds,  and  hundreds  of  thousands,  but  the 
monad  is  the  common  boundary  of  all  numbers;  thus  also  with  respect  to 
things,  we  may  say  that  the  boundaries  of  sensibles  are  the  celestial 
bodies,  of  the  celestial  bodies  intelligible  essences,  and  of  all  things  in 
common  the  first  cause.     And  this  may  be  said  in  answer  to  those  who 


252  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

which  do  not  stration  must  consist  of  things  prior  and  more 
reciprocate.  known,  as  it  is  impossible  that  the  same  should 
be  prior  and  posterior  to  the  same,  unless  in  a  different  way, 
as  for  instance,  some  things  with  reference  to  us,  but  others 

simply  in  the  manner  in  which  induction  makes 
*y,\ldfv^chatiT  known.*"  If  however  this  be  so,  to  know  simply 
also  Metap.        will  not  be  well  defined,  but  it  is  two-fold,1  or  the 

other  demonstration  is  not  simply  so  which  is  pro- 
1 1  e.  of  the      (Juced  from  things  more  known  to  us.t    Still  there 

on,  seech.  13.  °  .  I 

happens  to  those  who  assert  there  js  demonstra- 
tion in  a  circle,  not  only  what  has  now  been  declared,  but  that 
they  say  nothing  else  than  this  is  if  it  is,  and  in  this  manner 
we  may  easily  demonstrate  all  things.  Nevertheless  it  is  evi- 
dent that  this  occurs,  when  three  terms  are  laid  down,  for  to 
assert  that  demonstration  recurs  through  many  or  through 
few  terms,  or  whether  through  few  or  through  two,  makes  no 
.   ,,        ,         difference.     For  when  A  existing,  B  necessarily 

4.    K xampic .  ** 

is,  and  from  this  last  C,  if  A  exists  C  will  exist, 
if  then,  when  A  is,  it  is  necessary  that  B  should  be,  but  this 
existing,  A  exists,  (for  this  were  to  demonstrate  in  a  circle,) 
let  A  be  laid  down  in  the  place  of  C.  To  say  therefore  that 
because  B  is  A  is,  is  equivalent  to  saying  that  C  is,  and  this 
is  to  say  that  A  existing  C  is,  but  C  is  the  same  as  A,  so  that 
it  happens  that  they  who  assert  there  is  demonstration  in  a 
circle,  say  nothing  else  than  that  A  is  because  A  is,  and  thus 
we  may  easily  demonstrate  all  things.  Neither  however  is 
this  possible,  except  in  those  things  which  follow  each  other 

as  properties :  from  one  thing  however  being 
hook^'ch^T    laid  down,  it  has  been  proved  %  that  there  will 

never  necessarily  result  something  else,  (I  mean 
by  one  thing,  neither  one  term,  nor  one  thesis  being  laid 
down,)  but  from  two  first  and  least  theses,  it  is  possible  (to 
infer  necessarily  something  else),  since  we  may  syllogize. 
If  then  A  is  consequent  to  B  and  to  C,  and  these  to  each 

subvert  demonstration  by  a  procession  to  infinity,  that  we  not  only  say 
there  is  demonstration,  but  that  things  do  not  proceed  to  infinity,  because 
there  is  a  certain  principle  of  demonstration  by  which  we  know  the  terms 
or  boundaries  of  things,  when  we  obtain  illumination  from  thence.  Per- 
haps, however,  by  a  "  certain  principle  of  science,"  Aristotle  means  our 
intellect,  and  by  terms,  axioms.    Cf.  Metap.  lib.  ii.  and  x. 

1  The  one  from  things  more  known  and  prior,  according  to  nature ;  the 
other  from  those  more  known  and  prior,  according  to  us. 


nnxr.  iv.]  the  postertop  analytics.  253 

other,  and  to  A,  thus  indeed  it  is  possible  to  demonstrate 
all  those  things  which  are  required  from  each  other  in  the 
first  figure,  as  we  have  shown  in  the  books  on    *  Anal.  Prior, 
Syllogism.*     It  has  also  been  shown  f  that  in  the   book _"• eh- 5- 
other  figures  there  is  either  not  a  syllogism,}  or   et  se'q; c  '   ' 
not  one  concerning  the  subjects  assumed  ;l  but  it    t  (circulo.) 
is  by  no  means  possible  to  demonstrate  in  a  circle    Buhle- 
those  which  do  not  reciprocate.     Hence,  since  there  are  but 
few  such  in  demonstrations,  it  is  evidently  vain  and  impossi- 
ble to  say,  that  there  is  demonstration  of  things  from  each 
other,   and  that  on  this  account  universal  demonstration  is 
possible. 

Chap.  IV. —  Upon  the  terms  "  every"  "per  se,"  and  "  universal." 

Since  it  is  impossible  that  a  thing,  of  which  there 
is  simply  science,  should  have  a  various  subsist-  demonstration* 
ence,  it  will  be  also  necessary  that  what  we  know 
should  pertain  to  demonstrative  science,  and  demonstrative 
science  is  that  which  we  possess  from  possessing  demon- 
stration, hence  a  syllogism  is  a  demonstration  from  neces- 
sary (propositions).  We  must  comprehend  then  of  what, 
and  what  kind  (of  propositions),  demonstrations  consist ;  but 
first  let  us  define  what  we  mean  by  "  of  every,"  and  "  per 
se,"  and  "  universal." 

I  call  that  "  of  every,"  which  is  not  in  a  cer- 
tain thing,  and  in  another  certain  thing  is  not,  nor  t;"on  "(feom"* 
which  is  at  one  time,  and  not  at  another ;  as  if  nV" 
animal  is  predicated  of  every  man,  if  it  is  truly 
said  that  this  is  a  man,  it  is  true  also  that  he  is  an  animal, 
and  if  now  the  one  is  true,  so  also  is  the  other ;  and  in  like 
manner,  if  a  point  is  in  every  line.  Here  is  a  proof,  for  when 
we  are  questioned  as  it  were  of  every,  we  thus  object,  either 
if  a  thing  is  not  present  with  a  certain  individual,  or  if  it  is 
not  sometimes.  But  I  call  those  "  per  se  "  which  3.  of "  To  ko.0* 
are  inherent  in  (the  definition  of)  what  a  thing   ai™>' '  Per 

1  Both  assumed  prop,  are  not  proved,  because  in  the  2nd  fig.  the  con- 
clusion is  negative,  wherefore  we  cannot  prove  an  affirmative  prop,  in  a 
circle  ;  and  in  the  3rd  fig.  the  conclusion  is  particular,  wherefore  an  uni- 
Yersal  cannot  be  demonstrated  in  a  circle. 


TO  kcltu  navrot. 


254  aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

is,!  as  line  is  in  triangle,  and  point  in  line,  (for 
Hnean/poTnt.    *hft  essence  of  them  is  from  these,*  and  they  are 

in  the  definition  explaining  what  it  is:)2  also 
those  things  which  are  inherent  in  their  attributes  in  the 
definition  declaring  what  a  thing  is,3  as  the  straight  and  the 
curved  are  inherent  in  a  line,  and  the  odd  and  even  in 
-  As  3  5  7  number,  and  the  primaryf  and  composite,!  tne 
&c  '  '  '  equilateral  §  and  the  oblong  :4  and  they  are  inhe- 
t  As  9,  i.  e.       rent  in  all  these,  in  the  definition  declaring  what 

3,  3, 3,  &c.         a  t^g  jS)  tnere  inciee(i  iine)  but  here  number. 

number.S(1Uare  IQ  a  similar  manner,  in  other  things,  I  say  that 

Taylor.  such  are  per  se  inherent  in  each,  but  what  are 

4.  of  accidents,  in  neither  way  inherent  (I  call)  accidents,  as  the 
fcf^Phys°Tib.  being  musical,  or  white  in  an  animal.  Moreover, 
lib  e\Metap'  tnat  which  is  not  predicated  of  any  other  subject, 

as  that  which  walks  being  something  else,  is  that 
which  walks,  and  is  white,  but  essence  and  whatever  things 
signify  this  particular  thing,  not  being  any  thing  else,  are  that 
which  they  are.  Now  those  which  are  not  predicated  of  a 
subject,  I  call  "  per  se,"  but  those  which  are  so  predicated,  I 
call  accidents.  Again,  after  another  manner,  that  which  on 
account  of  itself  is  present  with  each  thing  is  "  per  se,"  but 
that  which  is  not  on  account  of  itself  is  an  accident  ;5  thus  it 
is  an  accident  if  while  any  body  was  walking  it  should  lighten, 
for  it  did  not  lighten  on  account  of  his  walking,  but  we  say 
that  it  accidentally  happened.  If,  however,  a  thing  is  present 
on  account  of  itself,  it  is  per  se,  as  if  any  one  having  his  throat 

1  Four  senses  are  given  of  this  expression,  to  KaO'  avro:  1.  When  the 
predicate  is  part  of  the  definition  of  the  subject.  2.  When  the  subject  is 
part  of  the  definition  of  the  predicate.  3.  When  existence  is  predicated 
of  a  substance.  4.  When  the  subject  is  the  external  efficient  cause  of  the 
predicate.  In  proper  demonstration,  propositions  must  be  "  per  se  " 
either  in  the  first  or  second  meaning.  Cf.  Mansel's  Logic,  note  H.  on 
the  Demonstrative  Syllogism. 

2  Thus  a  triangle  is  defined  to  be  a  figure  contained  by  three  straight 
lines. 

3  As,  to  use  Aristotle's  graphic  illustration,  in  the  definition  of  nose, 
flatness  of  nose  is  not  employed,  but  flatness  of  nose  is  defined  to  be  a 
curvature  of  nose. 

4  An  oblong  number  is  that  which  a  number  produces,  not  multiplied 
by  itself,  but  by  another  number,  as  six  is  from  twice  three.  Taylor. 

*  This  relates  to  the  efficient  cause. 


3HAP.  IV.]  THE   POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  255 

cut  should  die,  and  through  the  wound,  because  he  will  die  in 

consequence  of  his  throat  being  cut,  but  it  did  not  accideut- 

ally  happen  that  he  whose  throat  was  cut  died. 

Those  therefore  which  are   predicated  in  things   recapitulation. 

which  are  simply  objects  of  science  per  se,  so  as 

to  be  inherent  in  the  things  predicated,*  or  which   *  lst  mode- 

are  themselves  inherent  in  subjects,!  are  on  ac-    t  2nd  mode. 

count  of  themselves,  and  from   necessity,  for  it 

does  not  happen  that  they  are  not  inherent  either  simply  or  as 

opposites,  as  the   straight  and  the  curved  in  a  line,  and  the 

even  or  odd  in  number.     For  a  contrary  is  either 

privation  or  contradiction  in  the  same  genus,  as   contra^.18  a 

that  is  even  which  is  not  odd  in  numbers,  so  far 

as  it  follows  r1  hence  if  it  is  requisite  to  affirm  or  deny,  it  is 

also  necessary  that  those  which  are  per  se  should  be  inherent. 

Let  then  the  expressions  "  of  every  "  and  "  per    7 
se  "  be  thus  defined  :  I  call  that  universal,  however,   ™  "  afT<5, 

•  t  t  n  »i  quatenus  lp- 

which  is  both  predicated  "  of  every     and  "  per   sum,"  and  to 
se,"  and  so  far  as  the  thing  is.2     Now  it  is  evident   "^eT  ex" 
that  whatever  are  universal  are  inherent  in  things 
necessarily,  but  the  expressions  "  per  se,"  "  and  so  far  as  it 
is,"  are  the  same ;  as  a  point  and  straightness  are  per  se  pre- 
sent in  a  line,  for  they  are  in  it,  in  as  far  as  it  is  a  line,  and 
two  right  angles  in  a  triangle,  so  far  as  it  is  a  triangle,  for  a 
triangle  is  per  se  equal  to  two  right  angles.     But  universal  is 
then  present,  when  it  is  demonstrated  of  any  casual  and  pri- 
mary thing,  as  to  possess  two  right  angles  is  not  universally 
inherent  in  figure,  yet  it  is  possible  to  demonstrate  of  a  figure 
that  it  has  two  right  angles,  but  not  of  any  casual  figure,  nor 
does  a  demonstrator  use  any  casual  figure,  for  a  square  is  in- 
deed a  figure,  yet  it  has  not  angles  equal  to  two  right.     But 

1  Contraries  may,  however,  be  both  absent  from  a  subject,  as  a  body 
may  be  neither  white  nor  black  ;  but  the  even  and  odd  are  opposed  as 
contradictories,  so  that  one  of  them  must  be  present  in  a  subject.  Vide 
Categ.  ch.  10.  The  even  is  compared  to  the  not  odd,  because  it  is  neces- 
sarily consequent  to  it. 

2  As  man  is  risible,  because  every  man  is,  both  "  per  se  "  and  "  qua- 
tenus ipsum  ;"  upon  the  apparent  inconsistency  of  Aristotle  in  the  use  of 
the  word  KaOuXov,  see  Waitz,  1.  Ana.  Post.  p.  315.  The  reader  will  find 
some  valuable  remarks  upon  the  demonstratio  potissima,  especially  in 
reference  to  this  place,  in  Mansel's  Logic,  Appendix,  note  H.,  where  the 
example  is  regularly  stated. 


256  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  r. 

any  isosceles  has  angles  equal  to  two  right,  yet  not  primarily, 
for  triangle  is  prior.  Whatever  therefore  is  casually  first 
demonstrated  to  possess  two  right  angles,  or  any  thing  else,  in 
this  first  is  the  universal  inherent,  and  the  demonstration  per 
se  of  this  is  universal,  but  of  other  things  after  a  certain 
manner  not  per  se,  neither  is  it  universally  present  in  an 
isosceles,  hut  extends  farther. 

Chap.  V. — Of  Errors  about  the  primary  Universal} 

We  ought  not  to  be  ignorant  that  frequently  error  arises,  and 
that  what  is  demonstrated  is  not  primarily  universal,  in  so 
far  as  the  primarily  universal  appears  to  be  demonstrated. 
l.  Sources  of  Now  we  are  deceived  by  this  mistake,  when 
error  in  effect-  either  nothing   higher  can  be   assumed,  except 

ing  universal  ,  .  .  .  ,  . 

demonstration,  the  singular  or  singulars,  or  when  something 
Example.  ejge  can   ^Q  ^gum^  \)Ut  jt  wants  a  name  in 

things  differing  in  species,  or  when  it  happens  to  be  as  a 
whole  in  a  part,  of  which  the  demonstration  is  made,  for 
demonstration  will  happen  to  particulars,  and  will  be  of  every 
individual,  yet  nevertheless  it  will  not  be  the  demonstration 
of  this  first  universal.  Still  I  say  the  demonstration  of  this 
first,  so  far  as  it  is  this,  when  it  is  of  the  first  universal.  If 
then  any  one  should  show  that  right  lines  do  not  meet,  it  may 
appear  to  be  (a  proper)  demonstration  of  this,  because  it  is  in 
all  right  lines,  yet  this  is  not  so,  since  this  does  not  arise  from 
the  lines  being  thus  equal,  but  so  far  as  they  are  in  some  way 
or  other  equal.  Also  if  a  triangle  should  be  no  other  than 
isosceles,  so  far  as  isosceles  it  may  appear  to  be  inherent : 

1  All  universals  are  gained  by  abstraction,  i.  e.  by  separating  the  phe- 
nomena in  which  a  certain  number  of  individuals  resemble  each  other, 
from  those  in  which  they  differ  ;  Locke  calls  all  universals,  abstract  ideas. 
Upon  generalization  as  distinguished  from  abstraction,  vide  Stewart,  Phil, 
of  the  Human  Mind  ;  Whately's  Logic,  Outline  of  Laws  of  Thought,  p. 
44.  The  causes  of  the  error  which  a  person  commits  who  demonstrates 
of  the  inferior  as  of  species,  what  he  ought  to  demonstrate  of  the  superior 
as  of  genus,  are  four.  1st,  When  one  particular  being  under  universal, 
we  demonstrate  the  former  instead  of  the  latter :  2nd,  when  we  demon- 
strate of  all  contained  under  a  proper  subject  when  we  seem  to  do  so  of 
the  proper  subject  itself :  3rd,  when  the  particular  is  demonstrated  be- 
cause the  universal  has  no  name  :  4th,  when  we  conclude  that  an  universal 
demonstration  of  a  thing  has  been  given  because  the  demonstration  is  of 
every  individual.     Of.  Waitz,  p.  387,  et  sea. 


CHAP.  V.]  THE   POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  257 

alternate  proportion  also,  so  far  as  regards  numbers  and  lines 
and  solids  and  times  (as  was  once  shown  separately)  it  is  possi- 
ble at  least  to  be  demonstrated  of  all  by  one  demonstration,  but 
inasmuch  as  all  these,  numbers,  length,  time,  are  not  one  deno- 
minated thing,  and  differ  from  each  other  in  species,  they  were 
assumed  separately.  But  now  the  demonstration  is  universal, 
for  it  is  not  in  so  far  as  they  are  lines  or  numbers,  that  it  is 
inherent,  but  in  so  far  as  this  thing  which  they  suppose  to  be 
universally  inherent.  For  this  reason  neither  if  one  should 
demonstrate  each  several  triangle  by  one  or  another  demon- 
stration, that  each  has  two  right  angles,  equilateral,  the 
scalene,  and  the  isosceles  separately,  would  he  yet  know  that 
the  triangle  (itself)  has  angles  equal  to  two  right,  except  in  a 
sophistical  manner,*  nor  triangle  universally, 
though  there  should  be  no  other  triangle  besides 
these.  For  he  does  not  know  it  so  far  as  it  is  triangle,  nor 
does  he  know  every  triangle,  except  according  to  number, 
but  not  every,  according  to  species,  even  if  there  be  no  one 
that  he  does  not  know.1  When  then  does  he  not  know  uni- 
versally, and  when  knows  he  simply  ?  It  is  clear  that  if 
there  is  the  same  essence  of  a  triangle,  and  of  an  equilateral 
either  of  each  or  of  all,  he  knows,  f2  but  if  there  is 
not  the  same,  but  different,  and  it  is  inherent  so  ^ e-  UIllvers" 
far  as  it  is  triangle,  he  does  not  know.3  Whether 
however  is  it  inherent,  so  far  as  it  is  triangle,  or  so  far  as  it 
is  isosceles  ?  And  when,  according  to  this,  is  it  primary  ? 
And  of  what  is  the  demonstration  universally  ?  It  is  evident 
that  it  then  is,  when,  other  things  being  taken  away,  it  is  in- 
herent in  the  primary,  thus  two  right  angles  will  be  inherent 
in  a  brazen  isosceles  triangle,  when  the  being  brazen  and  the 
being  isosceles  are  taken  away,  but  not  if  the  figure  or  bound- 
ary is  taken  away,  nor  if  the  primary  are.     But  what  pri- 

1  That  is,  in  number.  Triangles  are  here  said  to  be  as  many  in  num- 
ber as  in  species. 

2  Universally  and  simply  mean  nearly  the  same  thing,  because  when  a 
man  knows  not  sophistieally,  i.  e.  simply,  he  knows  universally,  hence 
Taylor  and  Buhle  insert,  the  one  "universally,"  the  latter  "  simpliciter," 
as  equivalent  in  this  place. 

a  That  is,  by  demonstration  of  a  species  of  triangle,  he  does  not  know 
the  universal  property  as  demonstrated  of  triangle,  viz.  the  possession  oi 
three  angles  equal  to  two  right. 

9 


258  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i 

mary  ?  if  indeed  triangle  (is  taken  away) ;  according  to  this 
it  is  inherent  in  others,  and  of  this  universally  is  the  demon- 
stration. 

Chap.  VI. — Demonstration  consists  of  Principles  per  se  ;  and  of  a 

necessary  Medium} 

If  then  demonstrative  science  is  from  necessary 
tion  ftrue  de*-"  principles,  (for  what  is  scientifically  known  cannot 
monstration       subsist  otherwise,)  and  those  which  are  per  se  in- 

only  from  ne-  »/  ...  /n 

cessary  propo-  herent  are  necessarily  so  in  things,  (tor  some  are 
sitions.  inherent  in  the  definition  of  what  a  thing  is,  but 

others  are  they  in  the  very  nature  of  which  the  subjects  are 
inherent,  of  which  they  are  so  predicated,  that  one  of  opposites 
is  necessarily  present,)  it  is  evident  that  the  demonstrative 
syllogism  will  consist  of  certain  things  of  this 
*  i.e.  of  propo-   kin(j  *  for  everv  thins;  is  either  thus  inherent,  or 

sitions  per  se.  '  J  ,  » 

according  to  accident,  but  accidents  are  not  ne- 
cessary. 

Either  therefore  we  must  say  this,  or  that  demonstration  is  a 
necessary  thing,  if  we  lay  down  this  principle,  and  that  if  de- 
monstration is  given  that  a  thing  cannot  subsist  otherwise, 
wherefore  thef  syllogism  must  be  from  necessary 
rnonstrative6      (matter).     For  it  is  possible  without  demonstra- 
tion to  syllogize  from  what  are  true,  but  we  can- 
not do  so  from  things  necessary,  except  by  demonstration,  for 
this  is  now  (the  essence)  of  demonstration.     An 
indication  also  that  demonstration  is  from  things 
necessary  is,  that  we  thus  object  to  those  who  think  they  de- 
monstrate that  (the  conclusion)  is  not  necessary,  whether  we 
think  that  the  matter  may  altogether  be  otherwise  possible,  or 
on  account  of  the  argument.     Hence  too  the  folly 
1   Reply  to         f  those  appears,  who  think  they  assume  princi- 

objection.  rr  '  .  .         •  ,     ,  ,  ■, 

pies  rightly,  if  the  proposition  be  probable  and 
true,  as  the  Sophists  (assume)  that  to  know  is  to  possess 
knowledge.2     For  it  is  not  the  probable  or  improbable,  which 

1  If  things  per  se  or  essential  are  necessary,  and  the  principles  of  de- 
monstration are  necessary  ;  therefore  the  principles  of  demonstration  are 
per  se.  As  Taylor  observes,  by  conversion  of  the  major,  Aristotle's  argu- 
ment here  may  become  a  syllogism  in  Barbara. 

2  It  was  thus  argued   by  Protagoras  :   Whoever  knows  any  thing,  pos- 


CHAP.    VI.]  THE    TOSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  259 

is  the  principle,  but  that  which  is  primary  of  the  genus  about 
which  the  demonstration  is  made,  nor  is  every  thing  true  ap- 
propriate.    But  that  it  is  necessary  that  the  syl-    2nd  pro(rf 
logism  should  consist  of  necessary  things  appears 
also  from  these ;  for  if  he  who  cannot  assign  a   #  The  major 
reason  why  a  thing  is,*  when  there  is  a  demon-    t  vide  2nd  ct 
stration,  does  not  possess  knowledge,!  let  A  J  be   *     ie  minor 
necessarily  predicated  of  C,  but  B  the  medium  through  which 
it  is  demonstrated  not  of  necessity,  (in  this  case)  he  does  not 
know  the  cause.     For  this  is  not  on  account  of  the  medium, 
for  the  latter  may  not  exist,  yet  the  conclusion  is  necessary. 
Besides,  if  some  one  does  not  know,  though  he  now   3 
possesses  a  reason,  and  is  safe,  the  thing  also  be- 
ing preserved,  he  not  having  forgotten  it,  neither  did  he  bo 
fore  know  it.     But  the  medium  may  perish  if  it  is  not  neces- 
sary, so  that  he,  being  safe,  will  have  a  reason,  § 
the  thing  being  preserved,  and  yet  not  know  it,    LnuBuMe! 
wherefore  neither  did  he  know  it  before.1     But 
if  the  medium  is  not  destroyed,  yet  may  possibly  perish,  that 
which  happens  will  be  possible  and  contingent,  it  is  impossi- 
ble however  that  one  so  circumstanced  should  know.2 

When  therefore  the  conclusion  is   from  neces-   3.  if  the  con- 

,  .  ..  -i.  elusion   be  ne- 

sity,  there  is  nothing  to  prevent  the  medium  Cessary,thePre- 
through  which  the  demonstration  was  made  from  ™^%nu¥wne0n 
being  not  necessary,  since  it  is  possible  to  syllogize  the  latter  are  so 
the  necessary  even  from  things  not  necessary,  just  musw>°  neee£ 
as  we  may  the  true  from  things  not  true.  Still  sary. 
when  the  medium  is  from  necessity  the  conclusion  is  also  from 
necessity,  as  the  true  (results)  from  the  true  always :  for  let 
A  be  of  necessity  predicated  of  B,  and  this  of  C,  then  it  is 

sesses  science :  he  who  possesses  science  knows  what  science  is  :  there- 
fore, he  who  knows  any  thing  knows  what  science  is. 

1  Scientia  quam  quis  habet,  non  perditur,  nisi  aut  ipse  perit  ant 
obliviscitur  aut  res  quam  scivit,  intent.  Waitz.  For  a  general  analysis 
of  the  argument,  see  Waitz,  page  320,  in  locum. 

J  Vide  Prior  Anal,  book  ii.  chap.  2 — 4.  The  argument  that  the  me- 
dium, the  source  of  science  as  containing  the  cause,  does  not  perish,  though 
it  may  do  so,  and  therefore  by  its  remaining  that  science  may  be  possessed. 
Aristotle  shows  to  be  ineffectual,  since  they  who  advance  it  are  compelled 
to  confess  that  to  be  possible,  viz.  that  the  medium  may  perish,  which  is 
impossible,  and  hence  that  we  may  be  ignorant  of  what  we  know.  By 
being  "so  circumstanced,"  is  meant  "to  Ik-  ignorant  without  ibrgoiful- 
ness  "     Ci.  Whately's  Logic,  b.  iv.  c.  ii.  sec.  2. 

s  2 


260  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

necessary  that  A  should  be  with  C.  But  when  the  conclu- 
sion is  not  necessary,  neither  possibly  can  the  medium  be  ne- 
cessary :  for  let  A  be  present  with  C,  not  of  necessity,  but  let 
it  be  with  B,  and  this  with  C  of  necessity  ;  A  then  will  also  be 
of  necessity  present  with  C,  yet  it  was  not  supposed  so.1 
Since  therefore  what  one  knows  demonstratively  must  be  in- 
herent of  necessity,  we  must  evidently  obtain  the  demonstra- 
tion through  a  necessary  medium  also,  for  otherwise,  he  will 
neither  know  why  a  thing  exists,  nor  that  it  is  necessary  for 
it  to  exist,  but  he  will  either  imagine  not  knowing,  if  he 
assumes  what  is  not  necessary  as  if  it  were  necessary,2 
or  in  like  manner  he  will  not  imagine  if  he    knows   that 

it  is  through  media,  and  why  it  is  through  the 

immediate.*3 
Of  accidents  however  which  are  not  per  se  after  the  man- 
ner in  which  things  per  se  have  been  defined,  there  is  no  de- 

1  The  necessary  relations  between  premises  and  conclusion  may  be 
considered  as  four  : 

1.  If  the  conclusion  is  necessary,  the  propositions  may  be  non-neces- 
sary. 

2.  If  the  conclusion  is  non-necessary,  the  prop,  are  non-necessary. 

3.  If  the  prop,  are  necessary,  the  conclusion  is  always  necessary. 

4.  If  the  prop,  are  non-necessary,  the  conclusion  may  be  necessary. 
Granting  that  the  last  (number  4.)  may  be  true,  yet  Aristotle  denies 
that  in  such  a  case  the  person  who  thus  infers  demonstrates,  because 
demonstration  produces  true  science,  but  such  a  man  is  ignorant  that  the 
conclusion  is  necessary.     Vide  also  Hill's  Logic,  p.  285,  et  seq. 

2  Sanderson  defines  thus :  Error  est  habitus  quo  mens  inclinatur  ad 
assentiendum  sine  formidine  falsitati.  Opinio  est  habitus  quo  mens  in- 
clinatur ad  assentiendum  cum  formidine  alicui  proposition!  propter  proba- 
bilitatem  quam  videtur  habere.  Error,  therefore,  as  Mansel  observes, 
implies  certainty  of  the  subject,  but  not  of  the  object;  whilst  opinion  can- 
not consist  with  certainty  of  the  subject,  nor  yet,  strictly,  with  that  of  the 
object.  It  is  of  course  clear,  that  what  one  may  scientifically  know, 
another  may  only  think,  but  to  constitute  real  science  two  things  are 
necessary  :  1.  A  correct  ascertainment  of  the  data  from  which  we  are  to 
reason ;  2.  Correctness  in  deduction  of  conclusions  from  them.  Cf. 
Whately,  b.  iv.  c.  2,  sect.  3.  Error,  as  defined  above,  comes  under  the 
state  of  mind  described  in  the  text  bv  Aristotle. 

3  Cf.  Aquinas,  Op.  48,  cap.  1 ;  Occam,  Log.  p.  3,  c.  2.  If  the  premise 
is  not  the  first  cause,  though  it  contains  the  cause  of  the  conclusion,  the 
syllogism  is  not  Si  a/u<rajv,  and  there  is  no  demonstration  :  neither  if 
the  premise  be  an  effect  and  not  a  cause  of  the  conclusion,  nor  if  the  pre- 
mise, though  immediate,  be  a  remote  cause  of  it,  since  in  all  these  cases 
we  know  the  fact  only,  but  not  the  cause.  Cf.  Mansel  and  Wa'Js  Log. 
'ib.  iii.  cap.  22. 


CHAP.  VII.]  THE   POSTERIOR  ANALYTICS.  261 

monstrative  science,  since  it  is  not  possible  to  de- 

'        .  „  *     .  ,  4.  The  non-rie- 

monstrate  the   conclusion    ot   necessity,  because   cessary,  not  to 
accident  may  possibly  not  be  present,  for  I  speak   ^spuuuond  in 
of  accident  of  this  kind.1     Still  some  one  may 
perhaps  doubt  why  we  must  make  such  investigations  about 
these  things,  if  it  is  not  necessary  that  the  conclusion  should 
be,  for  it  makes  no  difference  if  any  one  interrogating  casual 
things  *  2  should  afterwards  give  the  conclusion  :        , 
nevertheless  we  must  interrogate  not  as  it  (the   (cf.  Rhetoric, 
conclusion)  were  necessary  on  account  of  things   Jo/phy.ubfiLl 
interrogated,  but  because  it  is  necessary  for  him 
who  asserts  these  should  assert  this,  and  that  he  should  speak 
truly  if  the  things  are  truly  inherent. 

Since,  however,  whatever  are  inherent  per  se  . 

7  .,      .    ,  ,     .  i  5.  Necessity  of 

are  necessarily  inherent  in  every  genus,  and  so   the  minor  and 

far  as  each  is,  it  is  clear  that  scientific  demonstra-   ^0aJ°rb^osi" 

tions  are  of  things  "  per  se"  inherent,  and  consist   "per  se." 

of  such  as  these.     For  accidents  are  not  neces-   t  An.  Post.  u. 

sary  :  f  wherefore  it  is  not  necessary  to  know  the 

conclusion  why  it  is,  nor  if  it  always  is,  but  not  "  per  se,"3 

as,  for  instance,  syllogisms  formed  from  signs.| 

For  what  is  "  per  se  "  will  not  be  known  "  perse,"   J^  £het- 

nor  why  it  is,  and  to  know  why  a  thing  is,  is  to 

know  through  cause,  wherefore  the  middle  must  "  per  se  "  be 

inherent  in  the  third,  and  the  first  in  the  middle. 

Chap.  VII. — Tliat  we  may  not  demonstrate  by  passing  from  one 
Genus  to  another.* 

It  is  not  therefore  possible  to  demonstrate  pass-   kdemonltrT 
in°-  from  one  srenus  to  another,  as,  for  instance,   tion,  viz.  a  de 

1  i.  e.  about  common  accident— for  proper  accident  is  predicated  in 
the  second  mode  per  se  of  a  subject.    Taylor. 

8  Ad  veram  demonstrationem  nihil  attinet  si  quis  sumat  quae  in  casu 
posita,  et  mutationi  obnoxia  sint  et  qua?  inde  consequantur,  declarer. 
Waitz.  The  casual,  here  alluded  to,  are  propositions  not  belonging  to 
the  conclusion. 

3  If  it  always  is  inherent,  i.  c.  if  the  propositions  be  always  true. 

*  Cf.  Anal.  Post.  i.  10.  Eth.  i.  '2.  Kcckennann  Syst.  Log.  ni.  Tract. 
2.  cap.  1.  Zabarella  de  Meth.  lib.  ii.  cap.  7.  Genus  lure  signifies  the 
object  or  materia  circa  quarn,  often,  but  improperly,  called  the  sub- 
ject; the  species  are  the  subdivisions  of  the  general  subject.     In  the 


262  Aristotle's  org  anon.       [book  i 

monstrated  (to  demonstrate)  a  geometrical  (problem)  by 
conclusion,  ax    arithmetic,  for  there  are  three  things  in  demon- 

10ms,  and  the  .  1     •         i      • 

subject  genus,  strations,  one  the  demonstrated  conclusion,  and 
•  Th  b  ^'1S  is  that  which  is  per  se  inherent  in  a  certain 
concluded  of  genus.*  Another  are  axioms,  but  axioms  are 
the  subject.  ^ey.  from  which  (demonstration  is  made),  the 
third  is  the  subject  genus,  whose  properties  and  essential 
+  cf  Aquinas  accidents  demonstration  makes  manifest. f  Now 
Opusc  48,  c  it  is  possible  that  the  things  from  which  demon- 
stration consists  may  be  the  same,|  but  with  those 
I  Videch.  11.  wh0ge  genus  is  different,  as  arithmetic  and  geo- 
metry, we  cannot  adapt  an  arithmetical  demonstration  to  the 
accidents  of  magnitudes,  except  magnitudes  are  numbers,  and 
how  this  is  possible  to  some  shall  be  told  here- 
after. §  But  arithmetical  demonstration  always 
has  the  genus  about  which  the  demonstration  (is  conversant), 
and  others  in  like  manner,  so  that  it  is  either  simply  neces- 
sary that  there  should  be  the  same  genus,  or  in  a  certain  re- 
spect,1 if  demonstration  is  about  to  be  transferred ;  but  that 
2.  That  the  ex-  it  is  otherwise  impossible  is  evident,  for  the  ex- 
tremes and        tremes  and  the  middles  must  necessarily  be  of  the 

media  must  be  .  <f 

of  the  same  same  genus,  since  it  they  are  not  per  se,  they 
genus.  wjjj  ^e  accjc|ents     Qn  this  account  we  cannot  by 

geometry  demonstrate  that  there  is  one  science  of  contra- 
ries, nor  that  two  cubes  make  one  cube,2  neither  can  any 
science  (demonstrate)  what  belongs  to  any  science,  but  such 
as  are  so  related  to  each  other  as  to  be  the  one  under  the 
other,  for  instance,  optics  to  geometry,  and  harmonics  to 
arithmetic.  Nor  if  any  thing  is  inherent  in  lines  not  so  far  as 
they  are  lines,  nor  as  they  are  from  proper  principles,  as  if  a 
straight  line  is  the  most  beautiful  of  lines,  or  if  it  is  contrary 
to  circumference,  for  these  things  are  inherent  not  by  reason 
of  their  proper  genus,  but  in  so  far  as  they  have  something 
common. 

demonstrative  syllogism,  the  minor  term  is  the  subject;  the  major,  the 
attribute  ;  the  middle,  the  cause. 

1  Of  subaltern  sciences,  the  subject  is  not  entirely  the  same,  as  the 
subject  of  geometry  is  a  line,  but  of  optics  an  optical  line.  Taylor.  Vide 
also  Trendelenburg,  p.  ]  18. 

2  That  is,  geometry  cannot  teach  a  method  of  doubling  the  cube.  Vide 
Reimer  de  Duplicatione  Cubi.  Omnis  demonstratio  genus  suum,  non 
excedere  sed  in  eo  consistere  debet.    Waitz. 


CHAP.  VIII.  IX.]     THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  263 


Chap.  VIII. — Tilings  which  are  subject  to  Change  are  incapable 
of  Demonstration  per  se. 

It  is  also  evident  that  if  the  propositions  of  which  a  syllogism 
consists  are  universal,  the  conclusion  of  such  a  demonstration, 
and  in  short  of  the  demonstration  of  itself,  must  necessarily 
be  perpetual.     There  is  not  then  either  demon- 

1.  That  there 

stration,  nor  in  short  science  of  corruptible  na-  is  no  demon- 

tures,  but  so  as  by  accident,  because  there  is  not  finftVo°n  "°ere" 

universal  belonging  to  it,  but  sometimes,  and  after  se"  of  mutable 

a  certain  manner.     But  when  there  is  such,  it  is  caused  the 

necessary  that  one  proposition  should  not  be  uni-  universal  being 

non-existent. 

versal,  and  that  it  should  be  corruptible,  cor- 
ruptible indeed,  because  the  conclusion  will  be  so  if  the  pro- 
position is  so,  and  not  universal,  because  one  of  those  things 
of  which  it  is  predicated  will  be,  and  another  will  not  be,1 
hence  it  is  not  possible  to  conclude  universally,  but  that  it  is 
now.  It  is  the  same  in  the  case  of  definitions,  since  definition 
is  either  the  principle  of  demonstration,  or  demonstration, 
diifei'ing  in  the  position  (of  the  terms),  or  a  certain  conclusion 
of  demonstration.  The  demonstrations  and  sciences  however 
of  things  frequently  occurrent,  as  of  the  eclipse  of  the  moon, 
evidently  always  exist,  so  far  as  they  are  such,  but  so  far  as 
they  are  not  always,  they  are  particular,2  and  as  in  an  eclipse, 
so  also  is  it  in  other  things. 


C 


Chap.  IX. — That  the  Demonstration  of  a  thing  ought  to  proceed 
from  its  own  appropriate  Principles :  these  last  indemonstrable. 

Since  however  it  is  evident  that  we  cannot  de-    }  That  true 
monstrate  each  thing  except  from  its  own  prin-   demonstration 

1  Hoc  quidem  (tempore)  erit  quod  asseritur,  hoc  vero  (tempore)  non 
erit.  Buhle.  I  prefer  Buhle's  translation  for  its  clearness,  but  have  fol- 
lowed Taylor's  on  account  of  its  exactness.  The  science  of  things  sub- 
ject to  change  is  not  simply  science,  but  with  the  addition  of  Kara  avfi- 
/3$/3//(coc.  Upon  the  relation  of  science  to  its  subject  matter,  see  Rhet. 
book  i.  oh.  7.  Cf.  also  Rhet.  ii.  ch.  24.  Anal.  Prior,  i.  ch.  13.  The 
subject  of  science,  he  expressly  says  in  the  Ethics,  (b.  vi.  ch.  4,)  has  a 
necessary  existence,  therefore  it  is  eternal  and  indestructible. 

2  Particular  cases,  (of  eclipses,  for  instance,)  as  they  are  not  alf  syi 
tie  same,  do  not  fall  under  demonstration. 


264  aristotle's  organon.  [book  r. 

only  results  ciples,  if  what  is  to  be  demonstrated  is  inherent 

appnroprStePtoS  in  a  subject  so  far  as  the  subject  is  that  (which  it 

the  subject  of  js^  to  have  a  scientific  knowledge  of  that  thing  is 

the  terms  must  not  this,  if  it  should  be  demonstrated  from  true, 

either  be  homo-  indemonstrable,    and   immediate   (propositions).1 

geneous,  or  • ,  i  -r» 

from  two  ge-  .bor  we  may  so  demonstrate  possibly,  as  rJryso 
oneais°contain-  did,  the  quadrature  of  the  circle,  since  such  rea- 
ed  in  the  other,  sonings  prove  through  something  common,  that 
which  is  inherent  in  another  thing,  hence  these  arguments  are 
adapted  to  other  things  not  of  the  same  genus.2  Wherefore 
that  thing  would  not  be  scientifically  known,  as  far  as  it  is 
such,  but  from  accident,  for  otherwise  the  demonstration 
would  not  be  adapted  also  to  another  genus. 

We  know  however  each  thing  not  accidentally  when  we 
know  it  according  to  that,  after  which  it  is  inherent  from 
*  cf  Eth  b  vi  principles  which  are  those  of  that  thing,  so  far 
ch.  3.  as  it  is  that  thing  ;3*  as  that  a  thing  has  angles 

i  The  possession  equal  to  two  ri^ht  angles,  in  which   the  thing 

of  three  angles       ^  ,  „ ,    .  °        .    „=    .  »  „  -  .   ° 

equal  to  two  spoken  oi  j  is  essentially  inherent  Irom  the  pnn- 

i'gof  triangle.  c*ples  0I"  tnis  thing. J     Hence  if  that§  is  essen- 

§  ndtiou  or  tially  inherent  in  what  it  is  inherent,  it  is  neces- 

liimhete. '  e  sary  that  the  middle  should  be  in  the  same  affinity,  || 

II  i.  e.  with  the  but  if  not  yet  it  will  be  as  harmonics  are  proved 

extremes,  sub-  •  •  i  -i  •    1     *      n      i    a-l" 

ject,  and  pro-  through  an  arithmetical  principle.  ouch  things 
perty.  however  are  demonstrated  after  a  similar  manner, 

1  That  is,  the  propositions  must  also  be  appropriate  to  the  subject  of 
demonstration. 

3  According  to  Alexander  Aphrodisiensis — Bryso  endeavoured  to  de- 
monstrate the  quadrature  of  the  circle  thus  :  Where  the  greater  and  less 
are  found,  there  also  is  the  equal  found,  but  a  square  greater  and  less 
than  a  circle  is  found,  therefore  a  square  equal  to  the  circle  may  also  be 
found.  The  minor  is  proved,  because  a  square  inscribed  in  a  circle  is 
less,  and  ctVewmscribed  about  a  circle  is  greater  than  the  circle,  but  the  de- 
monstration is  founded  on  a  common  principle,  because  the  greater,  the 
less,  and  the  equal  are  found  not  only  in  a  square  and  circle,  but  also  in 
other  things.  Neither  is  the  major  universally  true,  because  a  rectilinear 
angle  may  be  given  greater  or  less  than  the  angle  in  a  semicircle,  but 
one  equal  to  it  cannot  be  given.    Vide  Euclid  Elem.  Prop.  xvi.  b.  3. 

3  The  examples  of  Aristotle  are  principally  taken  from  the  Mathe- 
matics, and  the  tests  of  ko.9'  clvto  and  y  avro  are  expressly  applied  to  a 
geometrical  theorem.     Mansel.     Vide  the  4th  chap,  of  this  book. 

4  That  is,  by  the  application  of  the  principle  of  a  superior  science,  to  a 
problem  belonging  to  a  subaltern  science,  as  music  is  subaltern  to  arith- 
metic. 


CHAP.  IX.]  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  265 

yet  they  differ,1  for  that  they  are,  is  part  of  another   *  r"ferior  sci" 
science,*  (for  the  subject  genus  is  another,  J)  but    \  \.  e.  differs 
why  they  are,  is  a  province  of  a  superior  science,   g^ySfc,. 
of  which  they  are  the  essential  qualities.     Hence   science, 
from  these  things  also  it  is  apparent  that  we  cannot  demon- 
strate each  thing   simply,   but  from   its   proper   principles, 
and   the   principles    of   these  %    have    something   t  of  subaltern 
common.  sciences- 

If  then  this  is  evident,  it  is  also  clear  that  it  2  That  the  ap_ 
is  impossible  to  demonstrate  the  proper  principles  propriate  prm- 
of  each  thing,  for  they  will  be  the  principles  of  tltagarettfem- 
all  things,  and  the  science  of  them  the  mistress  of  selves  incapa- 

.D  '       .     „    _  ,  .  .       ,./>       ble  of  demon- 

all  (sciences):2  for  the  man  has  more  scientific   stration.  what 

knowledge  who  knows  from  superior  causes,  since  1sscitehneCe_special 
he  knows  from  prior  things  when  he  knows  not 
from  effects,  but  from  causes.  So  that  if  he  knows  more, 
he  knows  also  most,  and  if  that  be  science,  it  is  also  more, 
and  most  of  all  such.  Demonstration  however  is  not  suitable 
to  another  genus,  except  as  we  have  said,  geometrical  to  me- 
chanical or  optical,  and  arithmetical  to  harmonical  demon- 
strations. 

Nevertheless  it  is  difficult  to  know  whether  a  , 

,         -•     3.  Difficulty  of 

man  possesses  knowledge  or  not,  since  it  is  hard  deciding  whe- 
to  ascertain  if  we  know  from  the  principles  of  ^J*  ^jj1^" 
each  thing  or  not,  which  indeed  constitutes  know- 
ledge.    We  think  however  that  we  know,  if  we  have  got  a 
syllogism  from  certain  primary  truths,  but  it  is  §  .  e  the  con 
not  so,  since  it  is  necessary  that  they  §  should  be  elusions  with 
of  a  kindred  nature  with  the  primary.  prmcip  es. 

1  Where  the  principle  is  assumed  from  the  same  science,  or  from  a 
superior  one,  the  difference  is,  that,  in  the  former  case,  the  oti  and  diori 
are  known ;  but  in  the  latter,  the  Swri  is  known  in  the  superior,  the  on 
in  the  inferior  science. 

*  Metaphysics.  See  the  third  book  of  Aristotle's  treatise  on  that  sub- 
ject; also  Magna  Moralia,  lib.  i. ;  Ue  Anima,  books  i.  ii.  iii. 


266  aristotle's  orgaston.  [book  i. 


•  Cf.  Metaph.     Chap.  X. — Of  the  Definition  and  Division  of  Prin 


books  v.  vi.  x 


ciples. 


1.  Definition  I  call  those  principles  in  each  genus,  the  exist- 
(,lpxa^1)Cthe7r     ence  of  which  it  is  impossible  to  demonstrate. 

as'sum'eT  'e^  Wnat  tlien  first  tnings>t  an<l  sucn  as  result  from 
ample.  '  these  signify,  is  assumed,  but  as  to  principles,  we 

t  vide  ch.  2.  must  assume  that  they  are,  but  demonstrate  the 
rest,  as  what  unity  is,  or  what  the  straight  and  a  triangle  are  ; 
it  is  necessary  however  to  assume  that  unity  and  magnitude 
exist,  but  to  demonstrate  the  other  things.1 

2  what  are  tll0se  wnicn  are  employed  in  demonstrative 

peculiar  to  each  sciences,  some  are  peculiar  to  each  science,  but 
wSmmon.   others  are  common,   and  common   according  to 

analogy,  since  each  is  useful,  so  far  as  it  is  in  the 
genus  under  science.  The  peculiar  indeed  are  such  as,  that 
a  line  is  a  thing  of  this  kind,  and  that  the  straight  is,  but  the 
common  are,  as  that  if  equals  be  taken  from  equals  the  re- 
mainders are  equal.  Now  each  of  these  is  sufficient,  so  far 
as  it  is  in  the  genus,  for  (a  geometrician)  will  effect  the  same, 
though  he  should  not  assume  of  all,  but  in  magnitudes  alone, 
and  the  arithmetician  in  respect  of  numbers2  (alone). 
2  liia  Proper  principles,  again,  are  those  which  are 

assumed  to  be,  and  about  which  science  considers 
whatever  are  inherent  per  se,  as  arithmetic  assumes  unities, 
and  geometry  points  and  lines,  for  they  assume  that  these  are, 

Th         m     ancl  that  tiiey  are  tJlis  Partlcular  thing. $     But  the 

that  theylre?6  essential  properties  of  these,  what  each  signifies, 

arid  what  they    they  assume,  as  arithmetic,  what  the  odd  is,  or 

the  even,  or  a  square,  or  a  cube ;   and  geometry, 

1  The  above  clears  Aristotle  from  the  charge  unjustly  brought  against 
him  by  Mill,  since  the  former  states  here  the  necessity  of  assuming  the 
existence  of  the  subject,  as  clearly  as  the  latter  asserts  it.  (Vide  Mill's 
Logic,  vol.  i.)  The  principles  (e£  wv)  from  which  Aristotle  demonstrates 
are  axioms  of  which  he  gives  a  specimen  below :  "  If  equals,  &c." 
Vide  the  table  of  the  principles  of  science,  given  before.  Cf.  also  Euclid, 
b.  vi.  Prop.  11. 

2  The  geometrician  and  arithmetician  each  assume  the  principle,  only 
so  far  as  it  is  analogous  to  his  subject  science ;  thus  the  former  does  not 
assume  every  whole  to  be  greater  than  its  part,  but  that  every  magnitude 
is  so,  and  the  latter  that  every  whole  number  is  greater  than  its  part.  Cf. 
Wait2  in  loc. 


CHAP.  X.]  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  267 

what  is  not  proportionate,  or  what  is  to  be  broken,  or  to  in- 
cline ;  but  that  they  are,  they  demonstrate  through    *  ;  e  pril]ci. 
things  common,*  and  from  those  which  have  been   P'es. 
demonstrated.!     So  also  astronomy,  for  all  de-    sions. 
monstrative    science    is    conversant   with    three   ?•  ^!l  demon- 

stration  con- 

things,  those  which  are  laid  down  as  existing,  versant  with 
and  these  are  the  genus,!  (the  essential  properties  ofwhich'we 
of  which   the   science  considers,)   and   common   sometimes  may 

ncclcct  two 

things  called  axioms,  from  which  as  primaries  %  \.  e.  the  siib- 
they  demonstrate  ;  and  thirdly,  the  affections,  §  §e  properties 
the  signification  of  each  of  which  the  demon-  Taylor.— Affec- 
strator  assumes.1  There  is  nothing  however  to  !!°passiones.  e' 
prevent  certain  sciences  overlooking  some  of  these,  Averrois. 
as  if  the  genus  is  not  supposed  to  be,  if  it  be  manifest2  that  it 
exists,  (for  it  is  not  similarly  manifest  that  number  is,  as  that 
the  cold  and  hot  are,)  and  if  (the  science)  does  not  assume  what 
the  affections  signify,  if  they  are  evident,  as  neither  does  it 
assume  what  things  common  signify,  (as  what  it  is)  to  take 
away  equals  from  equals,  because  it  is  known ;  nevertheless 
these  things  are  naturally  three,  viz.  that  about  which  demon- 
stration is  employed,  the  things  demonstrated,  and  the  prin- 
ciples from  which  they  are. 

Neither  however  hypothesis   nor  postulate  is   4  of  the  dif. 
that  which  it  is  necessary  should  exist  per  se,  and   ference  he- 
be  necessarily  seen,||  for  demonstration  does  not  w^IV^'and' 
belong  to  external  speech,  but  to  what  is  in  the   ?'2Wak,„ 
soul,-5  since  neither  does  syllogism.      t  or  it  is   p.  38,  App. 
always  possible  to  object  to  external  discourse, 


Waitz  in  loc. 


1  Vide  Trendelenburg  Erlaiiteringen,  p.  118.  For  a  full  enunciation 
of  the  statement  made  here  by  Aristotle,  the  reader  is  referred  to  Mansel's 
Logic,  p.  109,  and  Appendices. 

2  It  is  not  made  the  subject  of  hypothesis,  if  it  is  manifest;  in  other 
words,  it  is  tacitly  assumed. 

3  The  two  kinds  of  speech  were,  1st,  Xoyoc  6  t£w,  ical  Trpo^opiKog,  Kai 
Kara  ti)v  (pojviiv,  i.  e.  the  external,  and  ('2nd)  the  internal,  6  taw,  icai 
ivSiaBtroQ,  Kal  Kara  Tr\v  ^\iv\i\v.  Plut.  in  Philo.  et  Damascen.  Both 
Whately  and  Aldrich  regard  language  as  the  principal  object  of  logic;  the 
former  declares  that  "  if  any  process  of  reasoning  can  take  place  in  the 
mind  without  any  employment  of  language,  orally  or  mentally,  such  a 
process  does  not  come  within  the  province  of  the  science  here  treated  of." 
Mansel,  on  the  contrary,  considers  "  the  laws  of  such  process,  equally 
with  any  other,  matters  of  logical  investigation."     The  reader  may  pro- 


268  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

but  not  always  to  internal.  Whatever  things  then,  being  de- 
monstrable, a  man  assumes  without  demonstration,  these,  if 
he  assumes  what  appear  probable  to  the  learner,  he  supposes, 
and  this  is  not  an  hypothesis  simply,  but  with  reference  to  the 
learner  alone  ;  but  if,  there  being  no  inherent  opinion,  or  when 
a  contrary  is  inherent,  the  demonstrator  assumes,  he  requires 
the  same  thing  to  be  granted  to  him.  And  in  this  hypothesis 
and  postulate  differ,  for  postulate  is  any  thing  sub-contrary  to 
the  opinion  of  the  learner,  which  though  demonstrable  a  man 
assumes,  and  uses  without  demonstration. 
5.  That  deflni-  Definitions  then  are  not  hypotheses,  (for  they 
tion  is  not  hy-  are  not  asserted  to  be  or  not  to  be,)  but  hypothe- 
ses are  in  propositions.  Now  it  is  only  necessary 
that  definitions  should  be  understood,  but  this  is  not  hypothe- 
sis, except  some  one  should  say  that  the  verb  to  hear  is  hypo- 
thesis. But  they  are  hypotheses,  from  the  existence  of  which, 
in  that  they  are,  the  conclusion  is  produced.  Neither  does 
the  geometrician  suppose  falsities,  as  some  say,  who  assert, 
that  it  is  not  right  to  use  a  false  (principle),  but  that  the 
geometrician  does  so,  when  he  calls  a  line  a  foot  long  when 
it  is  not  so,  or  the  line  which  he  describes  a  straight  line  when 
it  is  not  straight.  The  geometrician  indeed  concludes  nothing 
from  the  lines  being  so  and  so,  as  he  has  said,  but  concludes 
those,  which  are  manifested  through  these  (symbols).  More- 
over postulate  and  every  hypothesis  are  either  as  a  whole  or 
as  in  a  part,  but  definitions  are  neither  of  these.1 

fitably  compare  Locke's  Essay,  b.  iv.  5,  5,  and  6,  2 ;  also  Sanderson. 
The  former's  distinction  between  mental  and  verbal  propositions  is  well 
known.  The  words  in  the  text  are  only  enunciative  of  oral  as  con- 
trasted with  mental  reasoning,  but  are  not  decisive  against  Whately's 
opinion.  Vide  De  Anima,  b.  i.  and  iii. ;  Eth.  b.  i.  c.  13.  Dr.  Hessey 
speaks  sensibly  enough  of  the  "  absurdity  of  maintaining  that  logic  re- 
gards the  accident  of  the  external  language,  and  not  the  necessity  of 
the  internal  thought"  (p.  4,  Intro.  Schem.  Rhet.).  It  appears  to  be, 
after  all,  "  splitting  a  straw  ;  "  for  such  an  opinion  is  not  only  "  absurd," 
but  self-destructive,  we  never  do,  because  we  never  can,  practically 
adopt  it. 

1  Defmitio  ab  hypothesi  eo  differt  quod  nihil  edicit  de  existentia  rei 
quae  definitur :  nam  si  quis  contendat  definitionem,  licet  non  ponat  ali- 
quid  esse  vel  non  esse,  sed  intelligi  tantum  velit  id  quod  dicat,  tamen 
esse  hypothesin,  quodcunque  auribus  percipimus,  si  quod  dictum  est  in- 
telleximus,  hypothesis  dicenda  erit.  Verum  viroOkaiiQ  dicuntur  quibus 
positis  {pcrwv  ovtwv)  et  ex  quibus  aliud  quid  colligitur.     Alia  causa  cur 


CIIAP.  XI.]  THE    POSTKRIOK    ANALYTICS.  269 


Chap.  XL — Of  certain  Common  Principles  of  all  Sciences. 

That  there  should  then  be  forms,*  or  one  cer-   *  nsr,— spe- 
tain  thing  besides  the  many,  is  not  necessary,  to   cies'    Buh,e- 
the  existence  of  demonstration,1  but  it  is  necessary  truly  to 
predicate  one  thing  of  the  many,  for  there  will  not  be  the  uni- 
versal unless  this  be  so,  and  if  there  be  not  an  universal,  there 
will  not  be  a  medium,  so  that  neither  will  there 
be   a  demonstration.      It   is  essential  then  that   uo^n^exist 
there  should  be  one  and  the  same  thing,  which  is   without  €i&n, 
not  equivocal  in  respect  of  many  :  no  demonstra-   out  an  uni-  " 
tion  however  assumes  that  it  is  impossible  to  af-   ^rnsal  conceP- 
firm  and  deny  the  same  thing   at  one  and   the 
same  time,   unless  it   is  requisite  also  thus   to  demonstrate 
the  conclusion.     It  is   demonstrated   however  by  assuming 
the  first  f  to  be  true  of  the  middle,  and  that  it  is   t  i.  e.  the  ma- 
not  true  to  deny  it,  but  it  makes  no  difference  ior  Pr°P- 

definitio  non  appellari  possit  hypothesis  in  eo  est,  quod  hsec  aut  uni- 
versalis est  aut  particularis,  in  ilia,  vero  quod  subjectum  est  aequale  esse 
debet  ei  quod  pradicalur.  Waitz.  Vide  also  scheme  of  principles  of 
science.    Cf.  Locke's  Essay,  b.  iii.  4,  7.     Occam's  Logic,  part  i. 

1  The  Platonic  theory  of  Idea,  to  which  Aristotle  here  refers,  so 
highly  commended  by  St.  Augustine,  is  not  free  from  much  error, 
arising  from  Plato's  opinion  thai  the  ideas  in  man's  soul  are  inherently 
good.  The  remark  which  Aristotle  makes  in  this  place,  seems  chiefly, 
as  Taylor  thinks,  to  prevent  the  misconception  of  Plato's  theory,  by 
those  who  imagined  his  ideas  to  be  corporeally  separate  from  matter, 
and  not  incorporeal  forms  residing  in  a  divine  intellect ;  but  the  real 
case  is,  that  Aristotle  elsewhere  impugns  the  doctrine  of  the  idea  as  not 
practical.  Vide  Ethics,  lib.  i.  c.  6,  Browne's  note,  Bohn's  edition ;  also 
Metaphysics,  lib.  xii.  De  Anima ;  Brewer's  Ethics  ;  Ritter,  vol.  ii.  The 
province  of  the  Platonic  dialectic  was  to  investigate  the  true  nature  of  that 
connexion,  which  existed  between  each  thing  and  the  archetypal  form  or 
idea  which  made  it  what  it  was,  and  to  awaken  the  soul  to  a  full  remem- 
brance of  what  she  had  known  prior  to  her  being  imprisoned  in  the  body. 
Hence,  dialectic,  with  Plato,  is  the  science  of  the  immutable,  and  takes 
cognizance  of  the  universal  principle ;  in  fact,  is  an  object  identical  with 
the  Metaphysics  of  Aristotle,  whereas  the  dialectic  of  the  latter  partook 
of  the  essentially  practical  nature  of  his  mind,  and  is  merely  "the  art  of 
disputing  by  question  and  answer."  Cf.  Gorgias,  Theaitetus,  Meno,  and 
the  Commentaries  of  Syrianus,  and  upon  the  doctrine  of  universals,  see 
Locke's  Essay,  b.  iv. ;  Stewart,  Phil,  of  Human  Mind;  Whately's  and 
Mansel's  Logics. 


270  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

whether  we  assume  the  middle  to  be  or  not  to  be,  and  in  a 

similar  manner  also  in  respect  of  the  third.1  For 
e  major.  .^  ^aj.  ^e  granted  *  in  respect  of  which  it  is  true 
to  predicate  man,  even  if  (some  one  should  think  that  man 
is)  not  man,  (the  conclusion)  will  be  true,  if  only  it  is  said 
that  man  is  an  animal,  and  not  that  he  is  not  an  animal,  for 
+  sup  lvthe  **  w^  ^e  true  to  say  that  Callias,  even  if  he  be 
minor— caiiias  not  Callias,f  yet  is  still  an  animal,!  but  not  that 
js Thewnciu- *  which  is  n°t  an  animal.  The  cause  however  is, 
sion.  that  the  first  is  not  only  predicated  of  the  middle, 

of  what  is  can-  but  also  of  something  else,  in  consequence  of  its 
of  contradic-le  DemS  common  to  many,  so  that  neither  if  the 
tion  in  demon-  middle  be  that  thing  itself,  or  not  that  thing,  does 

it  make  any  difference  in  respect  to  the  conclu- 
sion.    But  the  demonstration  which  leads  to  the  impossible, 

assumes  that  of  every  thing  affirmation  or  nega- 
Prior,  book  ii.  tion  is  true,§  and  these  |  it  does  not  always  (as- 
Tayior.oms '       sume)  universally,  but  so  far  as  is  sufficient,  and 

it  is  sufficient  (which  is  assumed)  in  respect  of 
the  genus.  I  mean  by  the  genus,  as  the  genus  about  which  a 
„  „.,  person  introduces  demonstrations,  as  I  have  ob- 

H  Vide  ch.  10.     x  ,   .     „         _- 

served  betore."| 
„  All  sciences  communicate  with  each  other  ac- 

irion  principles  cording  to  common  (principles),  and  I  mean  by  com- 
c5;inLleveral  mon  those  which  men  use  as  demonstrating  from 
these,  but  not  those  about  which  they  demonstrate, 
nor  thai  which  they  demonstrate,  and  dialectic  is  (common)  to  all 
*  (Science.)  (sciences).  If  also  any  one*  endeavours  to  demon- 
metamh  j;.se"  strate  universally  common  (principles),  as  that  of 
vide  Metap.  every  thing  it  is  true  to  affirm  or  deny,  or  that  equals 
b'  U1"  remain  from  equals,  or  others  of  this  kind.     Dia- 

lectic however  does  not  belong  to  certain  things  thus  definite, 
f  i.  e.  it  is  con-  nor  to  one  particular  genus  ;  f  for  it  would  not 
versant  with  interrogate,  since  it  is  impossible  for  the  demon- 
strator to  interrogate,  because  the  same  thing  is 
t  Pr.  An.  b.  ii.  n°t  proved  from  opposites  : 2  this  however  has 
ch.  is.  been  shown  in  the  treatment  of  syllogism. t 

1  Though  the  minor  should  not  be  assumed  both  to  be  and  not  to  be 
that  which  it  is,  nevertheless  the  conclusion  will  be  right. 
*  Here  is  a  proof  of  the  difference  between  the  iialectic  of  Plato  and 


CHAP.  XII.  ]  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS. 


271 


Chap.  XII. —  Of  Syllogistic  Interrelation. 

If  syllogistic  interrogation  is  the  same  as  a  pro-  j   M  h 

position  of  contradiction,1  but  there  are  proposi-  deciding  what 

tions  in  each  science,  from  which  the  syllogism  [J^to'eTch6 

which  belongs  to  each  consists,  there  will  be  a  science, 

certain  scientific  interrogation,  from   which  the  M  , 

„       .         *       i  •    ,     •  ,         .  *  i.  e.  the  de- 

syllogism,    which  is  appropriate  to  each  science,   monstrative 
is  drawn.    It  is  clear,  then,  that  not  every  inter-    svll°sism- 
rogation  would  be  geometrical,  or  medical,  and  so  of  the  rest, 
but  from  what  any  thing  is  demonstrated  about  which  geo- 
metry is  conversant,  or  which  are  demonstrated  from  the  same 
principles  as  geometry,  as  optics,  and  in  like  man- 
ner with  other  sciences.      These  f  also  must  be   pr0ved  irTgeo- 
discussed  from  geometrical  principles  and  conclu-   metry,  &c. 
sions4  but  the  discussion  of  principles  is  not  to   ciuskmsfrom1 
be  carried  on  by  the  geometrician  so  far  as  he  is   the  former  be- 
such ;  likewise  with  other  sciences.     Neither  is   to^/subse- eS 
every  one  who  possesses  science  to  be  interrogated   i"6"1  demon- 

J  r   .  .  °  strations. 

with  every  question,  nor  is  every  question  about 
each  to  be  answered,  but  those  which  are  defined  about  the 
science.  It  is  evident  then  that  he  does  well,  who  disputes 
with  a  geometrician  thus,  so  far  as  he  is  such,  if  he  demon- 
strate any  thing  from  these  principles,  but  if  not,  he  will  not 
do  well.  Again,  it  is  clear  that  neither  does  he  confute  the 
geometrician  except  by  accident,  so  that  there  cannot  be  a 
discussion  of  geometry  by  those  who  are  ignorant  of  geometry, 
since  the  bad  reasoner  will  escape  detection,  and  it  is  the  same 
with  other  sciences. 

Since  there  are  geometrical  interrogations,  are   2.  of  discover- 
there  also  those  which  are  ungeometrical  ?  and   to  which  each* 


that  of  Aristotle,  pointed  out  above.  Moreover  the  dialectician  interro- 
gates so  that  his  opponent  may  either  affirm  or  deny,  but  the  demon- 
strator proves  or  interrogates  in  order  to  make  the  thing  evident  from 
principles  better  known  to  his  hearer;  again,  the  dialectician  may  em- 
ploy affirmation  or  negation,  but  the  demonstrator  has  to  prove  a  certain 
conclusion. 

1  Interrogation  and  proposition  are  the  same  in  reality,  but  differ  in 
definition.  A  proposition  is  such  as,  "  Every  man  is  an  animal;"  an 
interrogation  is  such  as,  "  Is  not  every  man  an  animal  ? "    Taylor. 


272  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  l 

false  syllogism  in  each  science  are  those  ignorant  questions  Avhich 
appertains.  are  0£  a  certain  quality1  geometrical?  whether 
also  is  a  syllogism,  from  ignorance,  a  syllogism  composed  from 
opposites  or  a  paralogism,2  but  according  to  geometry,  or  from 
another  art,  as  a  musical  interrogation  is  ungeometrical,  about 

geometry,  but  to  imagine  that  parallel  lines  meet 
subjectTerms6  ^s  *n  a  certain  respect  geometrical,*  and  after  an- 
are  so.  other  manner  ungeometrical  ?  t    For  this  ±  is  two- 

false.  fold,  in  the  same  way  as  what  is  without  rhythm  ; 

VometricaT1"     an<^  tne  one  *s  ungeometrical  because  it  possesses 

not  (what  is  geometrical),  as  what  is  without 
rhythm ;  but  the  other  because  it  possesses  it  wrongly — and 

this  ignorance  which  is  from  such  principles,  §  is 
prop°with  geo-  contrary.  ||  In  mathematics  however  there  is  not 
metrical  terms.   jn  jjj-g  manner  a  paralogism,  because  the  middle 

II  To  science.       .  £  f>         '  . 

is  always  two-told,"5  tor  (one  thing)  is  predicated 
of  every  individual  of  this,  and  this  again  of  another  every, 
but  the  predicate  is  not  called  universal  ;4  those,  nevertheless, 
it  is  possible,  we  may  see  by  common  percep- 
tion,^ but  in  argument  they  escape  us.  Is  then 
every  circle  a  figure  ?  If  any  one  should  delineate  it,  it  is  clear. 
But  what,  are  verses  a  circle  ?  They  are  evidently  not  so.5 

1  Ignorance  is  two-fold;  1st,  From  pure  negation;  2nd,  From  a  de- 
praved disposition.  Vide  chapters  16,  17,  and  18;  also  Eth.  b.  iii.  ch.  1. 
Cf.  Metap.  lib.  iii. 

2  Utrum  syllogismus  ayEw/xtrpjjroc  dicendus  est  is,  qui  fiat  ex  pro- 
positionibus  veritati  repugnantibus,  sive  etiam  qui  ex  propositionibus 
veris  non  recte  colligat  (6  irapaXoyto-^oc)  dummodo  propositiones  ex 
quibus  fiat  geometriae  sint  propria?  an  syll.  qui  ex  alia  doctrina  desumtus 
ad  geometriam  omnino  non  pertineat  ?  Waitz.  Aristotle  says  (after- 
wards) that  certain  interrogations,  entirely  geometrical,  are  assumed 
from  another  art  or  science,  and  correspond  to  the  ignorance  which  is 
said  to  be  of  pure  negation,  as  "  Is  number  even  or  odd  ? "  but  that  there 
are  others  which  are  in  a  certain  respect  geometrical,  and  in  a  certain 
respect  not,  and  which  are  falsely  conceived  of  geometrical  points,  as 
"  Will  not  parallel  lines  meet  ? "    Cf.  Philop.  fol.  34. 

3  That  is,  the  middle  term  is  twice  assumed,  viz.  in  the  major  and  in 
the  minor  prop. 

4  The  majus  extremum  is  universally  attributed  to  the  middle  term  in 
the  major  prop,  in  the  first  figure,  (to  which  Aristotle  refers,)  and  the 
middle  term  is  universally  attributed  to  the  minor  extreme  in  the  minor 
proposition ;  but  the  expression  of  universality  is  not  added  to  the  predi- 
cat?,  but  to  the  subject  only. 

•  I  read  the  concluding  paragraph  according  to  Waitz's  stopping.    Am- 


CHAP.  XII.]  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  2?3 

Still  it  is  improper  to  object  to  it,  if  it  be  an  in- 
ductive  proposition  ;*  tor  as  neither  is  that  a  pro-   1™*™-.. 
position  which  is  not  in  respect  of  many  things,    3  When     ob 
(since  it  will  not  be  in  all,  but  syllogism  is  from  jection  ie  not 
uriiversals,)  neither,  it  appears  clear,  is  that  an  ob- 
jection, for  propositions  and  objections  are  the  same,  as  the 
objection  which  one  adduces,  may  become  either 

t  Cf  ch   4 

a  demonstrative  or  a  dialectic  proposition.1! 

It  occurs  that  some  argue  contrary  to  syllogism,  4  instance  of 

from   assuming    the  consequences  of  both    (ex-  ajyllogistie 

tremes),  as  Caeneus  does,2  that  fire  is  in  a  mul-  Employing  J 

tiple  proportion,  because,  as  he  says,  both  fire  and  syllogism  with 

,.  .  .  „  -,         -n  both  prop,  af- 

this  proportion  are  rapidly  generated.  But  thus  firm,  in  the  2nd 
there  is  no  syllogism,3  though  there  will  be,  if  ngure- 

totle  says,  they  may  be  seen  by  common  perception,  ( tq  vorjcrii,)  the  verb 
vosTv  being  said  of  self-evident  truths,  because  mathematicians  represent 
these  things  by  diagrams,  and  therefore  if  a  circle  was  similarly  described, 
it  would  be  manifest ;  KvicXog  however  signifies  both  a  mathematical 
figure  and  a  kind  of  period  or  verse.    Vide  Hermo.  et  Demet. 

1  The  following  is  the  note  of  Julius  Pacius  on  Anal.  Prior,  c. 
28,  (Pacian  Division,)  as  to  the  apparently  conflicting  statement  made 
by  Aristotle  here.  "  Discrimen  ponit  Aristoteles  (lib.  ii.  Prior,  cap. 
28)  inter  objectionem  et  propositionem,  id  est  propositionem  illam  cui 
objicitur :  alioquin  etiam  ipsa  objectio  est  propositio,  ut  dictum  fuit  in 
definitione.  Discrimen  est,  quod  objectio  est  universalis,  vel  particu- 
laris :  propositio  vero,  si  sit  pars  syllogismi  universalis,  necessario  est 
universalis.  Sensus  est  propositiones  constituentes  syllogismum  esse 
universales  :  everti  autem  vel  per  objectiones  universales,  ut  contrarias ; 
vel  per  particulares  ut  contradicentes.  Huic  sententiae  opponitur  quod 
ait  Aristoteles,  lib.  i.  Post.  cap.  12,  par.  11,  omnem  instantiam  esse 
universalem.  Existimo  haec  loca  per  distinctionem  esse  concilianda. 
Aristoteles  in  Prior,  considerat  instantiam  sive  objectionem  quatenus 
evertit  propositionem  contrariam  ;  haec  objectio  potest  esse  tarn  universa- 
lis quam  particularis.  In  Poster,  autem  considerat  objectionem  quatenus 
per  earn,  non  solum  evertitur  propositio  adversarii,  sed  etiam  demon- 
stratio  erigitur.  Quoniam  igitur  demonstratio  constat  ex  propositionibus 
universalibus,  etiam  haec  objectio  necessario  est  universalis."  On  the  con- 
sideration of  the  enstatic  enthymeme,  and  of  the  passages  relative  to  the 
"Evaraaig,  vide  Dr.  Hessey's  Schem.  Rhet.  Supple.  Table  5.  Cf.  aUo 
Waitz  in  loc. 

2  Caeneus  argued  :   "  That  which  is  increased  by  multiple  proportion  is 

rapidly  increased 
Fire  is  rapidly  increased 
.  • .   Fire  is  increased  by  multiple  proportion." 
The  last  expression  means  that  by  every  addition  it  becomes  double  or 
triple,  etc. 

'  Because  both  prop,  affirm,  in  the  2nd  fig. 

7 


2/4  aristotle's  o::c:a:;on.  [book  i. 

the  multiple  is  consequent  to  the  most  rapid  proportion,  and 
the  most  rapid  proportion  to  fire  in  motion.  Sometimes  it 
does  not  happen  that  a  conclusion  is  made  from  the  assump- 
tions, and  sometimes  it  happens,  hut  is  not  perceived :  if 
however  it  were  impossible  to  demonstrate  the  true  from  the 
*  ,  ^ .  rf  false,  it  would  be  easy  to  resolve*  for  (the  terms) 
Prior  An.  b.  u.  would  be  necessarily  converted.1  lhus  let  Ay 
t  Propositions,  exist,  and  this  existing,  these  things  also  exist  J 
t  This  conciu-  fae  existence  of  which  I  know,  as  B,  from  these 
know  is  true,  then  §  I  will  demonstrate  that  that  ||  exists.  What 
sionheB?nclU  pertain  however  to  mathematics,  are  rather  con- 
II  The  proposi-  verted,  because  they  take  nothing  accidental,  (and 
in  this  they  differ  from  dialectical  subjects,)  but 
definitions. 

Yet  they  are  increased,  not  through  media,  but 

5.   Mathemati-  i        it   ■  i  ._•  a       j»  t>     a  •        ±- 

cai  demonstra-   through  additional  assumption,  as  A  of  r>,  this  ol 

nr  vl  Thely  ^»  tn*s  agam  °f  A  an&  so  on  to  infinity.  Also 
same,  by  many   transversely,  as  A  both  of  C  and  of  E,  as  there  is 

a  number  so  great  or  even  infinite,  which  is  A,  an 
odd  number  so  great  B,  and  an  odd  number  C.  A  then  is  (true) 

of  C,  and  the  even  is  a  number  so  great  D,  the 
ir  Example  (i).  eyen  number  ig  E  wherefore  A  is  (true)  of  E.f 

Chap.  XIII. — The  difference  between  Science,  "  that"  a  thing  is, 

and  "  why  "  it  is. 

l.  A  twofold     Now   there    is    a    difference    between    knowing: 

uiiiGrcncc  II  tuG 

syllogism  be       that  a  thing  is,  and  why  it  is,  first  in  the  same 

1  Difficilius  est  ad  dijudicandum  ex  quibus  propositionibus  coactum  sit. 
quod  syllogismus  confecit  {to  dvaXvetv).  Waitz.  Aristotle  means  that 
the  truth  of  the  prop,  might  easily  be  collected  from  the  truth  of  the 
conclusion,  for  they  might  be  converted. 

B  A 

Ex.  1.  Every  odd  number  is  finite  or  infinite 
C  B 

Every  ternary  is  an  odd  number 
C  A 

.  * .  Every  ternary  is  finite  or  infinite. 

D  A 

Every  even  number  is  finite  or  infinite 

E  D 

Every  binary  is  an  even  number 
E  A 

.  * .  Every  binary  is  finite  or  infinite 


CHAP.  XIII.]  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  275 

science,  and  in  this  in  two  ways,  the  one,  if  the   not  through 

'       .  ...  ,1  •  3'   j.         things  mime- 

syllogism  is  not  formed  through  things  immediate,   diate :  next,  if 
(since  the  primary  cause  is  not  assumed,  but  the   I^JJJ^L., 
science  of  the  why  has  respect  to  the  first  cause,)   in  the  same 
but  the  other  if  it  is  through  things  immediate   science> 
indeed,  yet  not  through  the  cause,  but  through  that  which  is 
more  known  of  the  things,  which  reciprocate.1     Now  nothing 
prevents  that  which  is  not  a  cause  being   sometimes  more 
known  amongst  things  which  are  mutually  predicated,  so  that 
demonstration  shall  accrue  through  this,  as  that  the  planets 
are  near,  because  they  do  not  twinkle.    Let  C  be  the  planets, 
B  not  to  twinkle,  A  to  be  near,  B  therefore  is  truly  predi- 
cated of  C,  since  the  planets  do  not  twinkle,  A  also  of  B,  for 
what  does  not  twinkle  is  near,  but  this  *  may  be   *  i.  e.  the  two 
assumed  by  induction  or  by  sense.2     It  is  neces-   propositions. 

1  When  the  effect  immediately  follows  the  cause,  the  two  are  said  to 
reciprocate,  because  one  being  admitted,  the  other  is  necessarily  so, 
though  sometimes  the  effect  is  more  known  than  the  cause,  as  he  says  be- 
low. For  the  two  senses  of  the  word  ayaaog,  cf.  Anal.  Post.  i.  2,  and  ii.  19 ; 
here  it  signifies  a  premise  immediate,  as  regards  its  conclusion,  i.  e.  not 
requiring  the  insertion  of  lower  middle  terms,  to  connect  its  terms  with 
those  of  the  conclusion.  On  the  particular  meaning  of  the  word  "  cause," 
and  in  fact  in  relation  to  the  whole  chapter,  see  Hill's  Logic,  under 
"  Demonstrationis  species."  pp.  287,  et  seq.,  and  Mansel's  Logic,  106, 
Appendix,  pp.  63,  et  seq. 

2  The  major  by  induction,  because  a  lamp,  gold,  etc.,  when  they  are 
near,  do  not  twinkle  ;  the  minor  by  sense,  because  we  see  the  planeta  fio 
not  twinkle.     Taylor. 

B  A 

Ex.  1.  Whatever  does  not  twinkle  is  near 
C  B 

The  planets  do  not  twinkle 
C  A 

.  • .  The  planets  are  near. 

B  A 

Ex.  2.  Whatever  is  near  does  not  twinkle        , 
C  B 

The  planets  are  near 

C  A 

.  • .  The  planets  do  not  twinkle. 

B  A 

Ex.  3.  What  is  spherical  is  thus  increased 
C  B 

The  moon  is  spherical 
C  K 

.' .  The  m:on  is  thus  increased. 


/ 


276  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

sary  then  that  A  should  be  present  with  C,  so 
of  th^s?!!6        ^hat  ^  *s  demonstrated  that  the  planets  are  near.* 

This  syllogism  then  is  not  ef  the  "  why,"  but  of 
the  "that"  (a  thing  is),  for  the  planets  are  not  near  because 
they  do  not  twinkle,  but  they  do  not  twinkle  because  they  are 
near.  It  happens  indeed  that  the  one  may  be  proved  through 
the  other,  and  the  demonstration  will  be  of  the  "  why,"  as  let 
C  be  the  planets,  B  to  be  near,  A  not  to  twinkle,  B  then  is 

present  with  C,  so  that  A  "not  to  twinkle"  will 
|,H(y   be  with  C.t   It  is  also  a  syllogism  of  the  "why," 

for  the  first  cause  was  assumed.  Again,  as  they 
show  the  moon  to  be  spherical  through  increments  (of  light), 
for  if  what  is  thus  increased  be  spherical,  and  the  moon  is  in- 
creased, it  is  evident  that  the  moon  is  spherical,  thus  then  a 

syllogism  of  the  "that"  is  produced,  but  if  the 
wmiddiVbe"1  middle  is  placed  contrarily,|  there  is  a  syllogism 
comes  the  ma-  of  the  "  why,"  for  it  is  not  spherical  on  account  of 
former  major  the  increments,  but  from  being  spherical  she 
becomes  the  receives  such  increments :  let  the  moon  be  C, 
§  Example (3.)  spherical  B,  increase  A.§  Where  again  the  media 
2.  Where  the  do  not  reciprocate,1  and  what  is  not  the  cause  is 
reciprocate°the  more  known,  the  "that"  is  indeed  demonstrated, 
on  is  demon-  but  not  the  "  why  ; "  further,  where  the  middle  is 
where  the  mid-  placed  externally,2  for  in  these  the  demonstration 
fyepiaceeXdtemal"  is  of  tlie  "that,"  and  not  of  the  "why,"  as  the 

cause  is  not  assigned.  For  example,  why  does 
not  a  wall  breathe  ?  because  it  is  not  an  animal,  for  if  this 
was  the  cause  of  its  not  breathing,  it  would  be  necessary  that 
animal  should  be  the  cause  of  its  breathing,  since  if  negation 
is  the  cause  of  a  thing  not  being,  affirmation  is  the  cause  of  its 
being,  thus  if  the  disproportion  of  hot  and  cold  is  the  cause 
of  not  being  well,  the  proportion  of  these  is  the  cause  of  be- 
ing well.  Likewise  if  affirmation  is  the  cause  of  being,  nega- 
tion is  the  cause  of  not  being,  but  in  things  which  have  been 
thus  explained,  what  has  been  stated  does  not  occur,  for  not 

1  The  cause  is  the  middle,  in  the  demonstration  of  the  "  «'%,"  and 
the  effect  is  the  middle,  in  the  demonstration  of  the  "that."  By  media 
not  reciprocating,  is  meant  when  we  reason  affirmatively,  from  the  effect 
to  the  remote  cause ;  as,  man  is  risible,  therefore  he  is  animal :  here  we 
miss  the  proximate  cause,  "is  rational." 

2  i.  e.  before  both  extremes,  in  the  2nd  figure,  in  which  demonstration 
through  a  remote  cause  (as  he  will  show)  occurs. 


CHAP.  Xm.l  THE   POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  277 

every  animal  respires.1  A  syllogism  of  such  a  cause  is  never- 
theless produced  in  the  middle  figure,  for  example,  let  A  be 
animal,  B  to  respire,  C  a  wall,  A  then  is  present  with  every 
B,  (for  whatever  respires  is  animal,)  but  with  no  C,  so  that 
neither  is  B  present  with  any  C,  wherefore  a  wall  does  not 
respire.*  Such  causes  however  resemble  things 
spoken  hyperbolically,2  and  this  is,  when  we  turn 
aside  to  speak  of  the  middle,  which  is  more  widely  extended, 
as  for  instance,  that  saying  of  Anacharsis,  that  amongst  the 
Scythians  there  are  no  pipers,  since  neither  are  there  any 
vines.3 

As  to  the  same  science  then,  and  the  position       Anoth    ... 
of  the  media,  these  are  the  differences  between  a  ference  be- 
syllogism  of,  that  a  thing  is,  and  of  why  it  is,  but   JJE'rffflKfci 
in  another  respect  the  why  differs  from  the  that,    ?nd  the  3'°™, 
because  each  is  beheld  in  a  different  science.  Now   each  belonging 
such  are  those  things  which  so  subsist  with  re-   t0.a  dlfferent 

o  .  science. 

ference  to  each  other,  as  that  the  one  is  under  the 
other,  such  as  optics  with  reference  to  geometry,  mechanics 
to  the  measurement  of  solids,  harmonics  to  arithmetic,  and 
celestial  phenomena  to  astronomy.  Some  of  these  sciences 
are  almost  synonymous,  as  astronomy  is  both  the  mathematical 
and  the  nautical;   and  harmony  is  both  mathematical  and 

'  But  only  those  which  have  lungs,  hence  the  proximate  cause  of 
respiration  is  not  animal,  but  the  possession  of  lungs,  which  cause  how- 
ever is  not  assigned. 

B  A 

Ex.  4.  Whatever  respires  is  an  animal 
C  A 

No  wall  is  an  animal 
C         B 
.  • .  No  wall  respires. 

2  Remote  causes  being  adduced  resemble  hyperboles,  in  that  more  is 
said  than  is  requisite,  for  a  remote  is  of  wider  extension  than  a  proximate 
cause. 

3  When  we  leave  (the  proximate  cause)  to  speak  of  that  middle  which 
is  more  widely  extended  than  (cause).  Taylor.  The  demonstration  of 
Anacharsis  is  thus  framed  in  the  2nd  figure.  There  are  no  pipers  where 
there  are  no  vines,  but  there  are  no  vines  among  the  Scythians,  . " .  among 
the  Scythians  there  are  no  pipers.  Now  the  successive  causes  to  the 
first  or  major  premise  are,  there  are  no  vines  because  there  are  no 
grapes ;  no  grapes  is  the  cause  of  no  wine ;  no  wine  is  the  cause  of  no 
intoxication;  no  intoxication  cause  of  no  pipers;  but  these  intermediate 
causes  are  omitted,  and  the  effect  is  at  once  connected  with  the  remote  cause. 


278 


ARISTOTLE  S    ORGANON. 


[book  I. 


that  which  belongs  to  the  ear.  For  here  to  know 
Sti  that  a  thing  is,  is  the  province  of  those  who  ex- 
beiongs  to  the  ercise  the  sense,  but  to  know  why  it  is,  belongs 
thel^to  the  to  mathematicians,  since  these  possess  the  demon- 
mathematicai,  strations  of  causes,  and  often  are  ignorant  of  the 
that,  as  they  who  contemplating  universals,  fre- 
quently are  ignorant  of  singulars  from  want  of  observation. 
But  these  *  are  such  as  being  essentially  something 
else  J  use  forms,  for  mathematics  are  conversant 
with  forms,  since  they  do  not  regard  one  certain 
subject,  for  though  the  geometrical  are  of  a  cer- 
tain subject,  yet  not  so  far  as  they  are  geometrical 
are  they  in  a  subject.J  As  optics  also  to  geome- 
try, so  is  some  other  science  related  to  optics,  as 
for  example,  the  science  about  the  rainbow,  for  to  know  that 
it  is,  appertains  to  the  natural  philosopher,  but  why  it  is,  to 
the  optician  either  simply  or  mathematically.  Many  sciences 
.  .      .,    ,.        also  which  are   not  arranged  under  each  other 

§  i.  e.  the  oTt  m  °     ,.    . 

is  known  in  subsist  thus,  §  for  example,  medicine  with  regard  to 
but  tneToVi  in  geometry,  for  to  know  that  circular  wounds  heal 
another.  more  slowly  is  the  province  of  the  physician,  but 

why  (they  do  so)  of  the  geometrician.1 


*  i.  e.  the  su- 
perior sciences 
+  Essentially 
different  from 
their  subject 
sciences. 

I  Cf.  Procli. 
Con.  in  Euclid 
Elem. 


Chap.  XIV. — The  first  Figure  most  suitable  to  Science. 

1  Mathemati-    Op  the  figures,  the  first  is  especially  adapted   to 
cai  demonstra-   science,  for  both  the  mathematical  sciences  carry 

1  Viz.  because  he  knows  that  the  capacity  of  the  circle  is  the  largest 
of  all  figures,  having  equal  perimeters,  hence  the  parts  of  a  circular 
wound  coalesce  more  slowly.  For  the  development  of  the  chapter,  the 
following  scheme  of  demonstration  is  introduced  : 

Demonstratio 


Quod  sit 

I 


Propter  quid  sit 


Obliqua 

per  deductionem 

ad  impossibile 


Directa 


Per  effectum 


Per  causam 
remotam 


Non  potissima 
per  causam 

proximam  quae 
non  est  prima 


Potissima 
per  causam 
proximam 
et  primam. 


CHAP.   XV.]  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  279 

out  their  demonstrations  by  this,  as   arithmetic,  tions  effected 

geometry,  optics,  and  nearly,  so  to  speak,  whatso-  fig™"egh  thls 
ever  sciences  investigate  the  "why,"  since  either 

entirely  or  for  the  most  part,  and  in  most  sciences,  2.  Also  the  syi 

the  syllogism  of  the  why  is  through  this  figure,  aX^cf.  book 

Wherefore  also,  on  this  account,  it  will  be  espe-  lnd-     .. 

.  .  '         .  .     .  '  .  r  3.  Also  the  sci- 

cially  adapted  to  science,  tor  it  is  the  highest  pro-  ence  of  roi  t» 

perty  of  knowledge  to  contemplate  the  "  why  ; "  *■"'"' 
in  the  next  place,  it  is  possible  through  this  figure  alone  to 

investigate  the  science  of  what  a  thing  is;  for  in  the  middle 
figure,  there  is  no  affirmative  syllogism,  but  the  science  of 

what  a  thing  is  belongs  to  affirmation,*  and  in  *  i.  e.  the  defi- 

the  last  figure,  there  is  an  affirmative,  but  not  an  nitlon  affirnii 

universal ;   but  the  what  a  thing  is  belongs  to  ^g^s  °0„!r 

universals,  for  man  is  not  a  biped  animal  in  a  densed  by  this 

certain  respect.     Moreover  this  has  no  need  of  t  j."  e.  they  are 

those,  but  they  are  condensed  f  and   enlarged  %  ^^^ the 

through  this,  till  we  arrive  at  things  immediate  :  §  1  By  prosyiio- 

it  is  evident,  then,  that  the  first  figure  is  in  the  fisime.'inde- 

highest  degree  adapted  to  scientific  knowledge.  monstrabie. 

Chap.  XV. — Of  immediate  negative  Propositions. 

As  it  happened  that  A  was  present  with  B  indi-    1.  That  one 
vidually,  so  also  it  may  happen  not  to  be  present,    sibTy^fbe^nl 
and  I  mean  by  being  present  with,  or  not,  indi-    dividuaiiy  pre- 
vidually,  that  there  is  no  medium  between  them,   other.    Exam- 
for  thus  the  being  present  with  or  not,  will  not  be    ples- 
according  to  something  else.     When  then  either  A  or  B  is  in 
a  certain  whole,  ||  or  when  both  are,  it  is  impos- 
sible that  A  should  not  be  primarily  present  with    Pr^rd?  ^j™1; 
B.     For  let  A  be  in  the  whole  of  C,  if  then  B  is 
not  in  the  whole  of  C,  (for  it  is  possible  that  A  may  be  in  a 
certain  whole,  but  that  B  may  not  be  in  this,)  there  will  be  a 
syllogism^  that  A  is  not  present  with  B,  for  if  C 
is  present  with  every  A,  but  with  no  B   A  will 
be  present  with  no  B.     In  like  manner  also,  if  B  is  in  a  cer- 
tain whole,  as  for  instance,  in  D,  for  D  is  with  every  B,  but 
A  with  no  D,  so  that  A  will  be  present  with  no   #  In  Cesare. 
B  by  a  syllogism.*     In  the  same  wayf  it  can  be   t  in  either  Ce- 


280  aristotle's  orgaxon.  [book  i. 

sare  or  Cames-  shown  *  if  both  also  are  in  a  certain  whole,  but 
*rThat  a  is  not  *hat  *'  *s  possible  that  B  may  not  be  in  the  whole 
with  B.  in  which  A  is,  or  again  A  in  which  B  is,  is  evi- 

dent from  those  co-ordinations  f  which  do  not  in- 
terchange.1    For  if  none  of  those,  which  are  in 
the  class  A  C  D,  is  predicated  of  any  of  those  in  B  E  F,  but 
A  is  in  the  whole  of  H,  which  is  co-arranged  with  it,  it  is 
evident  that  B  will  not  be  in  H,  for  otherwise  the 
t  Example  (i.)   co_or(iinates  woui<i  intermingle.} 

Likewise  also  if  B  is  in  a  certain  whole,  but  if 

2 

neither  is  in  any  whole,  and  A  is  not  present  with 
L  not* a  ifin-  B,  it  is  necessary  that  it  should  not  be  present 
demonstrable,  individually,  §  for  if  there  shall  be  a  certain  mid- 
dle, one  of  them  must  necessarily  be  in  a  certain  whole,  for 
there  will  be  a  syllogism  either  in  the  first,  or  in  the  middle 
figure.  If  then  it  is  in  the  first,  B  will  be  in  a  certain  whole, 
(for  it  is  necessary  that  the  proposition  in  regard  to  this 
should  be  affirmative,)  but  if  in  the  middle  figure 
either  of  them  ||  may  be  (in  the  whole),  for  the 
neSivePin°2nd  negative  being  joined  to  both,f  there  is  a  syllo- 
figure.  gism,*  but  there  will  not  be  when  both  the  pro- 

*  In  2nd  figure.    pogitions  are  negative. 

It  is  manifestly  possible  then,  that  one  thing  may  not  be 
individually  present  with  another,  also  when,  and  how  this 
may  happen,  we  have  shown. 

Chap.  XVI. — Of  Ignorance?  according  to  corrupt  position  of  the 
Terms,  where  there  are  no  Media. 

+,  ci'JSl  I2  '•■•    The  ignorance  t  which  is  denominated  not  ac- 

also  Eth.  b.  m.  ..     °  '. 

ch.  i.  cording  to  negation,  but  according  to  disposition. 

1  By  co-ordinations,  he  means  the  series  deduced  from  each  of  the  ten 
categories,  as  substances,  body,  etc.  Now  what  belongs  to  one  class  can- 
not be  arranged  in  another ;  thus  body,  which  is  in  the  category  of  sub- 
stance, cannot  be  in  the  category  of  quality. 


Ex.  1.  Substance.     H. 

B. 

Quality. 

Body.     A. 

E. 

Colour. 

Animated.     C. 

F. 

Whiteness. 

Rational.  \  -p. 
Animal.    ] 

8  Vide  Whately;  b.  in.  sec.  15- 

-19 

. 

CHAP.  XVI.]  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  281 

is  a  deception  produced  through  syllogism,  and  l.  Definitian  of 
this  happens  in  two  ways,  in  those  things  which  t?Je'eltv,£nd\ts 
are  primarily  present,  or  not  present ;  for  it  hap-  kinds. 
pens  either  when  one  simply  apprehends  the  being  present, 
or  not  being  present,  or  when  he  obtains  this  opinion  through 
syllogism :  of  simple  opinion,  then,  the  deception  is  simple,  but 
of  that  which  is  through  syllogism,  it  is  manifold.  For  let  A 
not  be  present  with  any  B  individually,  if  then  A  is  concluded 
to  be  present  with  B,  assuming  C  as  the  middle,  a  person  will 
be  deceived  through  syllogism.  Hence  it  is  possible  that  both 
propositions  may  be  false,  but  it  is  also  possible  that  only  one 
may  be  so,  for  if  neither  A  is  present  with  any  C,  nor  C  with 
any  B,  but  each  proposition  is  taken  contrary,  both  will  be 
false.  But  it  may  be  that  C  so  subsists  with  reference  to  A 
and  B,  as  neither  to  be  under  A  nor  universally  (present)  with 
B,  for  it  is  impossible  that  B  should  be  in  a  certain  whole, 
since  it  was  said  that  A  is  not  primarily  present  £xam  j 
with  it ;  but  A  need  not  be  universally  present  affirmative  de- 
with  all  beings,  so  that  both  propositions  are  false.  cePtlon- 
Nevertheless,  we  may  assume  one  proposition  as  true,  not 
either  of  them  casually,  but  the  proposition  A  C,  for  the  pro- 
position C  B  will  be  always  false,  because  B  is  in  none  ;  but 
A  C  may  be  (true),  for  instance,  if  A  is  present  individually, 
both  with  C  and  B,  for  when  the  same  thing  is  primarily  pre- 
dicated of  many  things,  neither  will  be  predicated  of  neither  ; 
it  makes  no  difference  however  if  it  (A)  be  not  individually 
present  with  it  (C). 

The  deception  then  of  being  present,  is  by  these   3  Negative  de- 
and  in  this  way  only,  (for  there  was  not  a  syllo-   ception  in- 
gism  of  being  present  in  another  figure,*)  but  the   first  and  middle 
deception  of  not  being  present  with,  is  in  the  first   ^By^  Anal 
and  middle  figure. t     Let  us  first  then  declare  in    Prior,  b.  i. 
how  many  ways  it  occurs  in  the  first,  and  under   omittedbe- 
what  propositional  circumstances.     It  may  then    cause  no  uni- 

VtTSHlCOTlClll- 

happen  when  both  propositions  are  false,  e.  g.  if  sion  proved  in 
A  is  present  individually  with  C  and  B,  for  if  A  ll- 
should  be  assumed  present  with  no  C,  but  C  with  every  B, 
the  propositions  will  be  false.  But  (deception)  is  possible, 
when  one  proposition  is  false,  and  either  of  them  casually  ; 
for  it  is  possible  that  A  C  may  be  true,  but  C  B  false ;  A  C 
true,  because  A  is  not  present  with  all  beings,  but  C  B  false3 


262 


ARISTOTLE  S    ORGANON. 


("book 


because  it  is  impossible  tbat  C  should  be  with  B,  with 
nothing  of  which  A  is  present ;  for  otherwise 
the  proposition  A  C  will  be  no  longer  true,* 
at  the  same  time,  if  both  are  true,  the  conclusion 
also  will  be  true.f  But  it  is  also  possible  that  C 
B  may  be  true,  when  the  other  proposition  is 
false,  as  if  B  is  in  C  and  in  A,  for  onef  must  ne- 
cessarily be  under  the  other,§  so  that  if  A  should 
be  assumed  present  with  no  C,  the  proposition 
will  be  false.  ||  It  is  clear  then,  that  when  one 
proposition  is  false,  and  also  when  both  are,  the 
syllogism  will  be  false.  % 

In  the  middle  figure,  however,  it  is  not  possible 
that  both  propositions  should  be  wholly  false,  for 
when  A  is  present  with  every  B,  it  will  be  impossible  to  assume 
any  thing,*  which  is  present  with  every  individual 
of  the  one,  but  with  no  individual  of  the  other  ;  j 
but  we  must  so  assume  the  propositions  that  the 
(middle)  may  be  present  with  one  (extreme),  and 
not  be  present  with  the  other,  if  indeed  there  is 
to  be  a  syllogism.^  If  then,  when  they  are  thus 
assumed,  they  are  false,  it  is  clear  that,  when  taken  contrarily, 
they  will  subsist  vice  versa,  but  this  is  impossible.1  Still 
there  is  nothing  to  prevent  each  being  partly  false,  as  if  C  is 
with  A,  and  with  a  certain  B  ;  for  if  it  should  be  assumed 
present  with  every  A,  but  with  no  B,  both  propositions  in- 
deed would  be  false,  yet  not  wholly,  but  partially.  The  same 
.  go  that  the  will  occur  when  the  negative  is  placed  vice  versa.  § 
neg.  prop,  is  But  it  is  possible  that  one  proposition,  and  either 
major.  q£  ^em,  may  ^e  faise>  for  what  is  present  with 

II  Because  b  is  every  A,  will  be  also  with  B,||  if  then  C  is  as- 
species  of  a.  sume(j  present  with  the  whole  of  A,  but  not  pre- 
sent with  the  whole  of  B,  C  A  will  be  true,  but  the  proposi- 
tion C  B  false.  Again,  what  is  present  with  no  B,  will  not 
be  present  with  every  A  ;  for  if  with  A,  it  would  also  be  with 
B,  but  it  was  not  present ;  if  then  C  should  be  assumed  pre- 
sent with  the  whole  of  A,  but  with  no  B,  the  proposition  C 

1  They  will  be  true  when  the  arrangement  is  such  that  negation  re- 
sults from  affirmation,  and  affirmation  from  negation ;  but  this  will  be 
impossible,  because  when  the  conclusion  is  false,  the  prop,  cannot  be 
true. 


*  Because  A  is 
with  some  C, 
viz.  with  B 
contained  un- 
der C 
t  Vide  An. 
Prior  i.  ch. 
2—4. 
t  A. 
§  C. 

||  i.e.  partially. 

If  i.  e.  the  con- 
clusion will  be 
false. 

2.  Middle  fig. 


*  Any  term. 
t  With  every 
A  and  no  B  in 
Camestres,  or 
with  no  A  and 
every  B  in 
Cesare. 
t  In  2nd  figure 


CHAP.  XVII.]  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  283 

B  will  be  true,  but  the  other  false.*     The  same   *  Either  wholly 
will  happen  if  the  negative  is  transposed,!  for   °^P^^iially• 

u    *  •     •  a         -li         -.1.        u     •  "D      -i-\\  tlfthenega- 

what  is  in  no  A,  will  neither  be  in  any  13  ;  it  then   tive  becomes 
C  is  assumed  not  present  with  the  whole  of  A,   the  major' 
but  present  with  the  whole  of  B,  the  proposition  A  C  will  be 
true,  but  the  other  false.4:    Again,  also,  it  is  false      Who]1  fahe 
to  assume  that  what  is  present  with  every  B,  is 
with  no  A ;  for  it  is  necessary,  if  it  is  with  every  B,  that  it 
should  be  also  with  a  certain  A ;  if  then  C  is  assumed  pre- 
sent with  every  B,  but  with  no  A,  the  proposition 
C  B  will  be  indeed  true,  but  C  A  false.  §     Hence,    %J^SS^ 
it  is  evident  that  when  both  propositions  are  false, 
and  when  one  only  is  so,  there  will  be  a  syllogism  deceptive 
in  individuals.1 


Chap.  XVII. — Continuation  of  the  same  with  Media. 

In  those  which  are  not  individually  present,||  or   ,  syllogism  of 
which  are  not  present,  when  a  syllogism  of  the   the  {&}s.e  p™-, . 

■  ductd  in  rowli- 

false  is  produced  through  an  appropriate  medium,  ates,  when  the 

both  propositions  cannot  be  false,  but  only  the  ^suVfe/a86' 

major.     But  I  mean  by  an  appropriate  medium,  medium. 

that  through  which  there  is  a  syllogism  of  contra-  _  . 

o  J       c  H  i.  e.  a  con- 

diction.^     For  let  A  be  with  B  through  the  me-    elusion  contra- 

dium  of  C,  since  then  we  must  take  C  B  as  af-   jggLfljJ? 

firmative,  if  there  is  to  be  a  syllogism,  it  is  clear   conclusion. 

that  this  will  be  always  true,  for  it  is  not  con-   „ 

verted.*     A  C,  on  the  other  hand,  will  be  false,   changed  into  a 

for  when  this  is  converted,  a  contrary  syllogism   ne*a,lve- 

arises.2    So  also  if  the  middle  is  assumed  from  another  affinity, 

as  for  instance,  if  D  is  in  the  whole  of  A,  and  is  predicated  of 

every  B,  for  the  proposition  D  B  must  necessarily  remain,3 

but  the  other  proposition  must  be  converted,4  so  that  the  one 

(the  minor)  will  be  always  true,  but  the  other  (the  major) 

always  false.     Deception  also  of  this  kind  is  almost  the  same 


1  In  those  cases  which  have  no  medium. 

2  A  syllogism  with  a  conclusion  opposite  to  the  true  conclusion,  and 
which  produces  deception  opposed  to  true  science. 

3  Because  the  minor  in  the  1st  fig.  must  continue  affirm. 
*  i.  e.  the  major  must  be  changed  into  a  negative. 


284  Aristotle's  okgaxon.  [book  i. 

2  Case  of  both  as  ^a*  wnicn  *s  through  an  appropriate  medium, 
propositions  but  if  the  svllogism  should  not  be  through  an  ap- 
bemg  false.  propriate  medium,1  when  indeed  the  middle  is 
under  A,  but  is  present  with  no  B,  it  is  necessary  that  both 
propositions  should  be  false.  For  the  propositions  must  be 
assumed  contrary  to  the  way  in  which  they  subsist,  if  a  syl- 
logism is  to  be  formed,2  for  when  they  are  thus  assumed  both 
are  false,  as  if  A  is  with  the  whole  of  D,  but  D  present  with 
no  B,  for  when  these  are  converted,  there  will  be  a  syllogism, 
and  both  propositions  will  be  false.  When  however  the  me- 
dium is  not  under  A,  for  instance,  D,  A  D  will  be  true,  but 
*  vide  An  "^  "^  false,  for  A  D  is  true,  because  D  was  not  in 
Prior,  b.  i.  ch.  A,  but  D  B  false,  because  if  it  were  true  the  con- 
2— 4-  elusion  also  would  be  true,*  but  it  was  false. 

3  Both  prop  Through  the  middle  figure  however,  when  de- 
cannot  be  ception  is  produced,  it  is  impossible  that  both 
riddle86  in  propositions  should  be  wholly  false,  (for  when  B 
figure,  when  i§  under  A,  it  is  possible  for  nothing  to  be  pre- 
produced.1S  sent  with  the  whole  of  the  one,  but  with  nothing 
t  vide  pre-  of  the  other,  as  has  been  observed  before, f)  but 
ceding  chapter.  Qne  proposition  may  be  false  whichever  may  hap- 
pen. For  if  C  is  with  A  and  with  B,  if  it  be  assumed  pre- 
sent with  A,  but  not  present  with  B,  the  proposition  A  C  will 
be  true,  but  the  other  false ;  again,  if  C  be  assumed  present 
with  B,  but  with  no  A,  the  proposition  C  B  will  be  true,  but 
the  other  false. 

4.  Affirmative  ^  tnen  the  syllogism  of  deception  be  negative, 

deception.  it  has  been  shown  when  and  through  what  the 

t  in  Barbara,  deception  will  occur,  but  if  it  be  affirmative^ 

when  it  is  through  an  appropriate  medium,  it  is  impossible 

§  Affirmative,  that  both  should  be  false,  for  C  B  must  necessarily 

figure!"*  Ut  remain,  §  if  there  is  to  be  a  syllogism, ||  as  was  also 

1TB From  being  observed  before.    Wherefore  C  A  will  be  always 

false.  false,  for  it  is  this  which  is  converted.^  Likewise 

1  When  it  is  through  a  medium  by  which  a  true  conclusion  cannot  be 
proved :  thus,  through  "  brute,"  it  can  never  be  proved  that  "  man  is  a 
living  being."     Taylor. 

2  i.  e.  to  form  a  negative  in  the  1st  figure,  (Celarent,)  it  is  necessary  in 
the  major  prop,  that  the  first  be  denied  of  the  middle,  and  in  the  minor 
that  the  middle  should  be  affirmed  of  the  last. 


CHAP.  XVIII.]         THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  285 

also,  if  the  middle  be  taken  from  another  class,  as  vas  ob- 
served in  negative  deception,  for  the  proposition  D  B  must 
of  necessity  remain,  but  A  D  be  converted,  and  the  decep- 
tion is  the  same  as  the  former.  But  when  it  is  not  through 
an  appropriate  medium,  if  D  be  under  A,  this*  t 
indeed  will  be  true,  but  the  other  t  false,  for  A 

....  .  ,  '  ,  .  ...      t  Ihe  minor. 

may  possibly  be  present  with  many  things  which 
are  not  under  each  other.1     If  however  D  is  not  under  A, 
this  |  will  evidently  be  always  false,  (for  it  is  as- 
sumed affirmative,)  for  D  B  may  be  as  well  true  as 
false,  since  nothing  prevents  A  being  present  with  no  D,  but 
D  with  every  B,  as  animal  with  (no)  science,  but  science  with 
(all)  music.    Again,  (nothing  prevents)  A  from  being  present 
with  no  D,  and  D  with  no  B :  it  is  clear  then  that  when  the 
medium  is  not  under  A,  both  propositions,  and  either  of  them, 
as  it  may  happen,  may  be  false. 

In  how  many  ways  then,  and  through  what,  syllogistic  de- 
ceptions are  possible,  both  in  things  immediate,  and  in  those 
which  are  demonstrated,  has  been  shown. 

Chap.  XVIII. —  Of  the  Dependence  of  Universals  upon  Induction, 
and  of  the  latter  upon  Sense. 

It  is  clear,  also,  that  if  any  sense  be  deficient,  a 

•  •  .  .1    Universals 

certain  science  must  be  also  deficient,  which  we   from  which  de- 
cannot  possess,  since  we  learn  either  by  induction   nionstratl°n 

,        -, r  .  _T  .  ■'.         .     „  proceeds,  de- 

or  by  demonstration.    JNow  demonstration  is  trom   pend  upon  m- 
universals,  but  induction  from  particulars,  it  is   ida"ter°upone 
impossible  however  to  investigate  universals,  ex-   sense-  (c'f-  Eth- 

r.     .,  ,       .      .       A.  °     ,  .  ,  .    ,  b.  vi.  ch.  3; 

cept  through  induction,  since  things  whicii  are    Rhet.  b.  i.  ch. 
said  to  be  from  abstraction,  will  be  known  through   23and  b'  "' ch' 
induction;2   if  any  one  desires  to  make   it  ap- 

1  The  expression,  present  with,  must  be  taken  generally,  for  the  being 
attributed,  whether  affirmatively  or  negatively,  to  many  things  not  un- 
der each  other;  thus  "  brute"  is  ailirmatively  attributed  to  "quadruped," 
but  negatively  to  "  man ; "  but  "  man  "  is  not  subjected  to  "  brute." 
Taylor. 

2  Vide  Hill's  Logic,  and  Aldrich  de  Prnedicab.  form.;  Whately's  Logic, 
book  ii.  ch.  5,  and  book  iv.  ch.  1.  Universals  are  gained  by  abstraction, 
because  we  separate  the  points  of  concord,  concomitant  with  a  certain 
number  of  individuals,  from  those  points  in  which  they  differ,  hence 
Locke  calls  all  universals  abstract  terms.    Properly  speaking,  abstraction 


286  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

parent  that  some  things  are  present  with  each  genus,  although 
they  are  not  separable,  so  far  as  eaeh  is  such  a  thing.  Never- 
theless, it  is  impossible  for  those  who  have  not  sense  to  make 
an  induction,  for  sense  is  conversant  with  singulars,  as  the 
science  of  them  cannot  be  received,  since  neither  (can  it  be 
obtained)  from  universals  without  induction,  nor  through  in- 
duction without  sense. 

Chap.  XIX. — Of  the  Principles  of  Demonstration,  whether  they  are 

Finite  or  Infinite. 

Every  syllogism  consists  of  three  terms,  and  one  indeed  is 
able  to  demonstrate  that  A  is  with  C  from  its  being  present 
with  B,  and  this  last  with  C,  but  the  other  is  negative,  having 
one  proposition  (to  the  effect)  that  one  certain  thing  is  in 
another,  but  the  other  proposition  (to  the  effect)  that  it  is  not 
with  it.  Now  it  is  clear,  that  the  same  are  principles,  and 
what  are  called  hypotheses,  since  it  is  necessary  to  demon- 
strate by  thus  assuming  these,1  e.  g.  that  A  is  present  with  C 
through  B,  and  again,  that  A  is  with  B  through  another  me- 
1.  By  those  dium,  and  that  B  is  with  C  in  like  manner.  By 
^aldTaf  ft  is  tnose  tnen  who  syllogize  according  to  opinion  only, 
to  be  consider-    and  dialectically,  this  alone  it  is  clear  must  be 

is  the  separation  of  one  portion  of  the  attributes  co-existing  in  any  object 
from  the  rest ;  hence,  in  this  sense,  Aristotle  applies  the  expression  here, 
rd  *£  cKpaipiatojg,  to  geometrical  magnitudes,  because  the  geometer  con- 
siders  only  the  properties  of  the  figure,  separating  them  from  those  of  the 
material  in  which  it  is  found.  (Cf.  An.  Post.  i.  ch.  5.)  "  Induction," 
says  Taylor,  "  is  so  far  subservient  to  the  acquisitions  of  science,  as  it 
evocates  into  energy  in  the  soul,  those  universals  from  which  demonstra- 
tion consists.  For  the  universal,  which  is  the  proper  object  of  science, 
is  not  derived  from  particulars,  since  these  are  infinite,  and  every  induc- 
tion of  them  must  be  limited  to  a  finite  number.  Hence  the  perception 
of  the  all  and  the  every  is  only  excited,  and  not  produced,  by  induction." 
Cf.  Trendelen.  de  An.  p.  478.  Biese  1.  Sententia  nostri  "loci  haec  est. 
Universales  propositiones  omnes  inductione  comparantur,  quum  etiam 
in  iis  qua?  a  sensibus  maxime  aliena  videntur  et  quae  ut  mathematica  (rd 
t£  atyatpkcreajc.)  cogitatione  separantur  a  materia  quacum  conjuncta  sunt, 
inductione  probentur  ea  quae  de  genere,  ad  quod  demonstratio  pertineat 
praedicentur  Ka9'  avrd  et  cum  ejus  natura  conjuncta  sint.  Inductio  au- 
tem  iis  nititur  quag  sensibus  percipiuntur  ;  nam  res  singulares  sentiuntur, 
scientia  vero  rerum  singularium,  non  datur  sine  inductione,  non  datur  in- 
ductio, sine  sensu.  Waitz.  Cf.  Metap.  b.  ii.  and  vi.;  De  Anima,  b.  iii.  iv. 
1  So  that  both  prop,  affirm,  or  one  affirms  and  the  other  denies. 


CHAP.  XIX. ]  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  287 

considered,  viz.  whether  the  syllogism  is  produced   ed  whether  the 
from  propositions  as  probable  as  possible,  so  that   arist  from*  pro- 
if  there  is  in  reality  a  medium  between  A  and  B,   positions  espe- 
but  it  does  not  appear,  he  who  syllogizes  through   cia  ypro 
this,  will  have  syllogized  dialectically.    But  as  to  truth,  it  be- 
hoves us  to  make  our  observations  from  things  inherent : '   it 
happens  thus.     Since  there  is  that,  which  is  itself  predicated 
of  something  else,  not  according  to  accident,*  but   »  Cf  ch  6 
I  mean  by  according  to  accident,  as  we  say  some- 
times, that  that  white  thing  is  a  man,  not  similarly  saying, 
that  a  man  is  a  white  thing,  for  man  not  being  any  thing  else 
is  white,  but  it  is  a  white  thing,  because  it  happens  to  a  man 
to  be  white:2  there  are  then  some  such  things  as  are  predi- 
cated per  se.     Let  C  be  a  thing  of  this  kind  which  is  not  it- 
self present  with  any  thing  else,  but  let  B  be  pri-    t  Immediatelv 
marily  f  present  with  this,  without  any  thing  else 
between.     Again,  also  let  E  be  present  in  like  manner  with 
F,  and  this  with  B,  is  it  then  necessary  that  this  should  stop, 
or   is  it  possible  to   proceed   to  infinity?3     Once   more,   it' 
nothing  is  predicated  of  A  per  se,  but  A  is  primarily  present 
with  H,  nothing  prior  intervening,  and  H  with  G,  and  this 
with  B,  is  it  necessary  also  that  this  should  stop,  or  can  this 
likewise  go  on  to  infinity?4    Now  this  so  much 
differs  from  the  former,  that  the  one  is,  whether  whetheTa1"17 
it  is  possible  by  beginning  from  a  thing  of  that   stated  series  of 

.  .  •  terms  proceeds 

kind, |  which  is  present  with  nothing  else,  but   to  infinity. 

something  else  present  with  it,  to  proceed  upward   ^  ^j°m  a 

to  infinity ;  but  the  other  is,  beginning  from  that 

which  is  itself  predicated  of  another,  but  nothing  predicated 

of  it, §  whether  it  is  possible  to  proceed  to  infinity 

downward.    Besides,  when  the  extremes  are  finite,    |ttribute.eme 

is  it  possible  that  the  media  may  be  infinite  ?    I 

mean,  for  instance,  if  A  is  present  with  C,  but  the  medium  of 

them  is  B,  and  of  B  and  A  there  are  other  media,  and  of 

these  again  others,  whether  it  is  possible  or  impossible  for 

these  also  to  proceed  to  infinity  ?    To  consider  this  however 

1   Whether  the  propositions  are  really  immediate. 

?  I  read  this  sentence  with  Buhle,  Bekker,  and  Waitz. 

*  So  that  a  first  predicate  may  not  be  found. 

*  So  that  a  last  subject  may  not  be  found. 


288 


Aristotle's  organon. 


book  T. 


is  the  same  as  to  consider  whether  demonstra- 
tions proceed  to  infinity,*  and  whether  there  is 
demonstration  of  every  thing, f  or  whether  there 
is  a  termination  (of  the  extremes)  relatively  to 
each  other.1 

I  say  also  the  same  in  respect  of  negative  syl- 
logisms and  propositions,  for  instance,  whether  A 
is  primarily  present  with  no  B,  or  there  will  be  a 
certain  medium  with  which  it  was  not  before  present,  as  if  G 
(is  a  medium),  which  is  present  with  every  B ;  and  again, 
with  something  else  prior  to  this,  as  whether  (the 
medium  is)  H,  which  is  present  with  every  G  ;  for 
in  these  also,  either  those  are  infinite  with  which 
first  they  are|  present,  or  the  progression  stops. 

The  same  thinsr  however  does  not  occur  in 
things  which  are  convertible,  since  in  those  which 
are  mutually  predicated  of  each  other,  there  is 
nothing  of  which  first  or  last  a  thing  is  predi- 
cated;2 for  in  this  respect  all  things  subsist  similarly  with 
respect  to  all,  whether  those  are  infinite,  which  are  predi- 
§  The  predi-  Rated  of  the  same,  or  whether  both  §  subjects  of 
catesand  sub-  doubt  are  infinite,  except  that  the  conversion  can- 
,ec  s'  not  be  similarly  made  ;  but  the  one  is  as  accident, 

but  the  other  as  predication.3 


»  Cf.  ch.  3. 
t  If  so,  there 
are  no  first 
principles,  for 
these  are  inde- 
monstrable. Cf. 
Metap.  lib.  i. 
and  ii. 

3.  The  same  as 
to  negatives. 


J  So  Waitz  and 
Bekker ;  but 
Taylor  and 
Buhle  read 
"  not  present." 

4.  The  doubt 
does  not  exist 
in  the  case  of 
reciprocals. 


1  i.  e.  whether  there  may  be  found  a  last  subject,  which  is  the  bound- 
ary of  the  progression  downward  from  the  first  attribute ;  and  also  whe- 
ther there  may  be  found  a  first  attribute,  by  which  the  progression  from 
the  last  subject  upward  will  be  terminated.  ITpoc  aWrjXa  7npaivta9ai, 
dicuntur  quorum  termini  medii  non  infiniti  sunt,  ut  sive  uno  sive  plurilms 
terminis  mediis  interjectis  major  cum  minore  continua  ratiocinatiune 
connectatur  in  conclusione.     Waitz. 

2  In  circular  proofs,  as  in  the  circle  itself,  there  is  not  a  first  nor  last. 

3  Whether  the  attributes  are  infinite,  in  terms  convertible,  they  may 
become  subjects,  or  whether  both  attributes  and  subjects  are  infmite,  the 
effect  is  the  same,  and  Aristotle  shows  that  these  investigations  may  be 
adapted  to  reciprocals,  when  one  is  per  se  predicated  of  the  other,  anc 
the  other  from  accident.  Excluding  the  last,  the  inquiry  is  whether  the 
subjects  and  predicates  which  are  so  per  se,  are  finite  or  infinite.  A 
thing  is  attributed  from  accident,  as  man  to  a  white  thing ;  but  per  se  as 
risibility  to  a  man.  Predication  therefore  is  now  assumed  for  attribute 
per  se,  as  will  be  shown  in  chap.  22. 


CHAP.  XX.  XXI.]    THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS. 


289 


1.  Media  not 
infinite  where 
the  predica- 
tions stop— Ex- 
planation and 
example. 


Chap.  XX.— Of  Finite  Media. 

That  media  cannot  be  infinite,  if  the  predica- 
tions, both  downward  and  upward,  stop,  is  evi- 
dent :  I  call  indeed  the  predication  upward,  which 
tends  to  the  more  universal,  but  the  downward 
that  which  proceeds  to  the  particular.  For  if 
when  A  is  predicated  of  F,  the  media  are  infinite,  that  is 
B,*  it  evidently  may  be  possible  that  from  A  in  a  *  a  is  the  high- 
descending  series,  one  thing  may  be  predicated  of  p'thptfifte! 
another  to  infinity,  (for  before  we  arrive  at  F,  there  ject,  b  the  me- 
are  infinite  media,)  and  from  F  in  an  ascending  se-  dia" 
ries,  there  are  infinite  (attributes)  before  we  arrive  at  A.  Hence, 
if  these  things  are  impossible,")"  it  is  also  impos- 
sible that  there  should  be  infinite  media  between 
A  and  F  ;  for  it  does  not  signify  if  a  man  should 
say  that  some  things  of  A  B  FJ  so  mutually  ad- 
here, as  that  there  is  nothing  intermediate,  but 
that  others  cannot  be  assumed. §  For  whatever 
I  may  assume  of  B,1  the  media  with  reference  to 
A  or  to  F,||  will  either  be  infinite  or  not,  and  it 
is  of  no  consequence  from  what  the  infinites  first 
begin,2  whether  directly  or  not  directly,  for  those 
which  are  posterior  to  them  are  infinite. 


t  That  there 
should  be  infi- 
nite subjects  to 
A,  and  infinite 
attributes  to  I'/ 
J  So  Waitz; 
Taylor  and 
Eekker,  A  B  ; 
Buhle,  A  B  C. 
§  Because  they 
are  infinite. 
II  The  media 
between  B  and 
F,  or  between 
B  and  A. 


Chap.  XXI. — It  is  shown  that  there  are  no  Infinite  Media  in 
Negative  Demonstration. 

It  is  apparent  also,  that  in  negative  demonstra-    !■  That  tliere 

..  i  .  .,,  .?.      ■,        -,   .  rr.  is  not  an  infin 

tion  the  progression  will  stop,  it  indeed  in  athrm-  ity  of  media  in 

ative  it  is  stopped  in  both  (series), \  for  let  it  be  n\X!tration~ 

impossible  to  proceed  to  infinity  upward  from  the  proved  in  the 

last,3  (I  call  the  last  that  which  is  itself  not  pre-  ft^boS*"" 

sent   with   any  thing   else,   but   something    else  ascending  and 

with  it,  for  instance,  F,)  or  from  the  first*  to  the  *  Predicate. 

1  i.  e.  whatever  medium  is  assumed  between  A  and  F ;  for  the  infinite 
media  between  A  and  F  are  signiiied  by  the  letter  B. 

-  Whether  from  either  (A  or  F)  of  the  extremes,  or  from  some  me- 
dium. Infinites  arc  directly  or  immediately  placed  from  A  or  from  F, 
but  not  directly  when  they  arc  from  some  medium. 

*  That  is,  in  affirmative  syllogisms,  upward  from  the  last  subject. 

u 


290  ARISTOTLE'S   OKGANON.  [BOOK   I. 

last,  (I  call  the  first  that  which  is  indeed  itself  predicated 
of  something  else,  but  nothing  else  of  it).  If  then  these 
things  are  so,  the  progression  must  stop  in  negation,  for  the 

not  being  present  is  demonstrated  triply,*  since 
figures16  three    either  B  is  present  with  every  individual  with 

which  C  is,  but  A  is  present  with  none  with 
which  B  is.  In  B  C  therefore,  and  always  in  the  other  pro- 
t  in  the  proof  position,!  it  is  necessary  to  proceed  to  immediates, 
of  the  minor,  for  this  proposition  is  affirmative.1  With  regard 
t  A;°thepredi-  to  the  other  ^  however  it  is  clear,  that  if  it  is  not 
cate  of  the         present  with  something  else  prior,  for  instance, 

major.  r  .  . 

§  Because  in  with  D,  it  will  be  requisite  that  this  (D)  should 
rn1dfid!eUiePhrL  be  present  with  every  B.§  Also  if  again  it||  is 
dicateofthe  not  present  with  something  else  prior  to  D,%  it 
II  i.  e  a.  will  require  that*  to  be  present  with  every  D,  so 

j  As  with  e.     tjiat   since    the    upward    progression   stops,   the 
downward  progression  will  also  stop,  and  there 
is  immediately   will  be  something  first  with  which  it  is  not  pre- 
demed.  sent.f     Moreover  if  B  is  with  every  A,  but  with 

no  C,  A  will  be  with  no  C  ;   again,  if  it  is  required  to  show 

I  viz  prop  b  this,!  it  is  evident,  that  it  may  be  demonstrated 
c.  either  through  the  superior  mode,§  or  through 

i.  e.  gure.  ^^  Qr  through  the  third,  now  the  first  has  been 
2-  spoken  of,  but  the  second  shall  be  shown.     Thus 

indeed  it  may  demonstrate  it,2  as,  for  instance,  that  D  is  pre- 
sent with  every  B,  but  with  no  C,  if  it  is  necessary  that  any 

II  as  D.  thing  ||  should  be  with  B,3  and,  again,  if  this^F  is 
*  which  'win  not  Present  Wlth  C>*  something  elsef  is  present 
be  shown.  with  D,  which  is  not  present  with  C,  wherefore 
f  As  E*  since  the  perpetually  being  present  with  some- 
thing superior  stops,  the  not  being  present  will  also  stop.  But 
the  third  mode  was  if  A  indeed  is  present  with  every  B,  but 
C  is  not  present,  C  will  not  be  present  with  every  A  ;4  again, 

1  It  is  assumed  that  there  is  no  infinite  progression  in  affirmative  prop., 
because  this  will  be  proved  in  the  following  chapter. 

2  The  syllogism  in  the  2nd  fig.  will  prove  B  to  be  predicated  of  no  C. 

5  In  order  that  a  syllogism  may  be  formed  in  Camestres ;  if,  on  the 
other  hand,  D  is  predicated  of  every  C,  and  of  no  B,  it  would  be  in 
Cesare. 

This  is  a  particular  prop.,  in  order  to  effect  a  syllogism  in  Bokardo, 
as  Aristotle  will  shortly  prove  it  in  the  third  figure ;  if  it  were  universal 
in  Felapton,  it  could  not  be  proved  in  this  figure. 


CHAP.  XXII.]  THE    POSTEKIOR    ANALYTICS.  291 

this   will   be    demonstrated   either   through    the 
above-mentioned  modes,*  or  in  a  similar  manner, f   2nd  figure.01 
in  those  modes  the  progression  stops,J  but  if  thus,    +  Through  the 
it  will  again  be  assumed  that  B  is  present  with   3. 
E,  with  every  individual  of  which  C  is  not  pre-    *  Vlde  above- 
sent.    ThisS  again,  also,  will  be  similarly  demon-    §  That  c  is  not 
strated,||  but  since  it  is  supposed  that  the  down-    u  in  the  3rd 
ward    progression    stops,    C   also,   which    is    not   ^gTtiat  is,  a  ne- 
present  with,1[  will  evidently  stop.  gative  prop. 

Nevertheless,  it  appears  plain,  that  if  it  should  not  be  de- 
monstrated in  one  way,  but  in  all,  at  one  time  from  the  first 
figure,  at  another  from  the  second  or  the  third,  that  thus  also 
the  progression  will  stop,  for  the  ways  are  finite,*    „ 
but  it  is  necessary  that  finite  things  being  finitely 
assumed  should  be  all  of  them  finite. 

That  in  negation  then  the  progression  stops,    t  Taylor  and 
if  it  does  so  in  affirmation,  is  clear, f  but  that  it    Bunie  end 
must  stop  in  them  |  is  thus  manifest  to  those  who   iein*afnnna- 
consider  logically.1  tions- 

Chap.  XXII. — That  there  are  no  Infinite  Media  in  Affirmative 

Demonstration. 

In  things  predicated  therefore  as  to  what  a  thing    j   of  predica. 
is,  this  is  clear,  for  if  it  is  possible  to  define,  or  if  tions,  as  to 

.1  p         ii  •  11  i.  what  a  thing 

the  very  nature  01  a  thing  may  be  known,  but   is,  there  cann, 
infinites  cannot  be  passed  through,  it  is  necessary   dftrJrenc^^f3 
that  those  things  should  be  finite  which  are  pre-   predication 
dicated  with  respect  to  what   a  thing  is.      We   pointed  out- 
must  however  speak  universally  thus :  a  white  thing  we  may 
truly  say  walks,  also  that  that  great  thing  is  wood ;  more- 
over, that  the  wood  is  great,  and  that  the  man  walks,  yet 
there  is  a  difference  between  speaking  in  this  way  and  in 

1  Aristotle  calls  those  arguments  logical  which  are  not  derived  from  the 
nature  of  a  thing,  but  analytical  are  opposed  to  them,  because  they  re- 
solve things  into  their  principles  ;  the  one  method  is,  as  Waitz  says,  an 
accurate  demonstration,  which  depends  upon  the  true  principles  of  the 
thing  itself;  the  other,  that  which  is  satislied  with  a  certain  probable 
ratiocination.  Cf.  Philop. ;  also  Biese  i.  p.  261  ;  Waitz  in  Inc.  Cicero 
(de  Finib.  i.  7)  calls  the  "  logical "  that  part  of  philosophy,  "  quae  sit  qua}* 
rendi  ac  disserendi." 

u  2 


not 


292  akistotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

that.  For  when  I  say  that  that  white  thing  is  wood,  then  1 
say  that  what  happens  to  be  white  is  wood,  but  what  is  white 
is  not,  as  it  were,  a  subject  to  wood,  since  neither  being  white, 
nor  what  is  a  certain  white  thing,  became  wood,  so  that  it  is  not 
(wood)  except  from  accident.    But  when  I  say  that  the  wood  is 

white,  I  do  not  say  that  something  else  is  white, 
*hIiVeiseS°me    kut  ifc  happens  to  that*  to  be  wood,  (as  when  I 

say  that  a  musician  is  white,  for  then  I  mean  that 
the  man  is  white,  to  whom  it  happens  to  be  a  musician,) 
but  wood  is  the  subject  which  became  (white),  not  being  any 
thing  else  than  what  is  wood,  or  a  certain  piece  of  wood.     If 

indeed  it  is  necessary  to  assign  names,  let  speak- 
ifs  white6  W°°d  ing  in  tais  way  j-  be  to  predicate,  but  in  that  way  J 
j  As  that  which  be  either  by  no  means  to  predicate,  or  to  predicate 
wood.  cf.  Met.  indeed,  not  simply,  but  according  to  accident. 
lib.  v.  Phy.  lib.   ^hat  which  is  predicated  is  as  white,  but  that  of 

which  it  is  predicated  as  wood  ;  now  let  it  be  sup- 
posed that  the  predicate  is  always  spoken  of  what  it  is  predi- 
cated of  simply,  and  not  according  to  accident,  for  thus  demon- 
strations demonstrate.  Therefore  when  one  thing  is  predi- 
cated of  one,  it  will  be  predicated  either  in  respect  of  what  a 
thing  is,  or  that  it  is  a  quality,  or  a  quantity,  or  a  relative, 
or  an  agent,  or  a  patient,  or  that  it  is  some  where,  or  at 
some  time. 

2.  Truepredi-  Moreover,  those  which  signify  substance,  sig- 
cations  either      nify  that  the  thing  of  which  they  are  predicated, 

define  what  the  *  .  °  J  r   .  .  ' 

subject  is,  or  is  that  which  it  is,  or  something  belonging  to  it, 
are  accidents,     j^j.  wiiatever  (j0  )10t  signify  substance,  but  are 

predicated  of  another  subject,  which  is  neither  the  thing  itself, 
nor  something  belonging  to  it,  are  accidents,  as  white  is  pre- 
dicated of  man,  since  man  is  neither  white,  nor  any  thing 
which  belongs  to  white,  but  is  perhaps  animal,  for  man  is 
that  which  is  a  certain  animal.  Such  as  do  not  signify  sub- 
stance it  is  necessary  should  be  predicated  of  a  certain  sub- 
ject, and  not  be  something  white,  which  is  white,  not  being 
any  thing  else.  For,  farewell  to  ideas,  for  they  are  mere 
prattlings,§  and  if  they  exist,  are  nothing  to  the 
subject,  since  demonstrations  are  not  about  such 
things.1 

*  Taylor  tells  us  quaintly,  "  that  Aristotle  is  not  serious  in  the  ob- 


CHAP.  XXII.]  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  293 

Again,  if  this  is  not  a  quality  of  this,  and  that  2 
of  this,  neither  a  quality  of  a  quality,  it  is  impos- 
sible that  they  should  be  thus  mutually  predicated  of  each 
other,  still  they  may  possibly  be  truly  said,  but  cannot  truly 
be  mutually  predicated.  For  will  they  be  predicated  as  sub- 
stance, as  being  either  the  genus  or  the  difference  of  what  is 
predicated  ?  It  has  been  shown  that  these  will  not  be  infinite, 
neither  in  a  descending  nor  in  an  ascending  progression,  as 
for  instance,  man  is  a  biped,  this  an  animal,  this  something 
else  ;  neither  can  animal  be  predicated  of  man,  this  of  Callias, 
this  of  something  else,*  in  respect  to  what  a  thing  *  L  e  in  an  in_ 
is.     For  we  may  define  the  whole  of  this  to  be   finite  series.  Cf. 

J  .     ,»     . .         •■  Phys.  lib.  iii. 

substance,  but  we  cannot  penetrate  infinites  by   +  Hence  they 
perception, f  wherefore  neither  are  there  infinites   are  incapable 
upwards  or  downwards,  for  we  cannot  define  that   of  definitlon- 
of  which  infinites  are  predicated.     They  will  not  indeed  be 
mutually  predicated  of  each  other  as  genera,  for  genus  would 
be  a  part  itself,  neither  will  quality  nor  any  of  the  other  cate- 
gories be  (mutually)  predicated,  except  by  accident,  for  all 
these  are  accidents,  and  are  predicated  of  sub-   3  In  either 
stances.     But  neither  will  there  be  infinites  in   case  there  can- 

.,_  p  ii-  i  ■  j-       not  be  an  jnli- 

ascending  series,!  tor  of  each  thing,  that  is  preen-   nite  series 
cated,  which  signifies  either  a  certain  quality,  or   nha^vr"fofTate-e 
a  certain  quantity,  or  something  of  this  kind,  or   gory. 
those  which  are  in  the  substance,  but  these  are   not  D!rfnfinite 
finite,  and  the  genera  of  the  categories  are  finite,   accidents. 
since  (a  category)  is  either  quality,  or  quantity,  or  relation,  or 
action,  or  passion,  or  where,  or  when.     One  thing  is  however 
supposed  to  be  predicated  of  one,§  but  those  not    §  ;.  e.  prop0Si. 
to  be  mutually  predicated  which  do  not  signify  J^y'ifjj1^1 
what  a  thing  is,  since  all  these  are  accidents,  but  theconjunction 
some  are  per  se,  others  after  a  different  manner,   ofattnbutes- 
and  we  say  all  these  are  predicated  of  a   certain  subject, 

jections  which  he  urges  against  Plato's  theory  of  ideas  ;  for  that  demon- 
stration cannot  exist  (from  the  testimony  of  Aristotle  himself)  unless  the 
existence  of  ideas  be  admitted  conformahly  to  the  doctrine  of  Plato,"  in 
total  opposition  to  what  is  stated  in  the  1 1  th  chap.  What  Aristotle  means 
is,  that  ideas,  even  if  they  exist,  are  of  little  use  to  effect  demonstration, 
because  the  latter  cannot  subsist  unless  there  be  iv  Kara  ttoWuiv;  but 
since  ideas  subsist  per  se,  (xwqhsto.  ttrnv,)  they  cannot  be  predicated  ol 
others.     Vide  also  Metap.  lib.  ix.  (x.)  and  lib.  xii   (xiii.)  ed.  Leipaic. 


294  Aristotle's  organon.  ["book  i 


L 


but  that  accident  is  not  a  certain  subject,  for  we  do  not  as- 
sume any  thing  of  this  kind  to  be,  which  not  being  any  thing 
else,  is  said  to  be  what  it  is  said  to  be,  but  we  say  that  it  is 
predicated  of  something  else,  and  certain  other  things  of 
another  thing.1  Neither  then  can  one  thing  be  predicated  of 
one  (infinitely)  upwards,  nor  downwards,  for  those  of  which 
accidents  are  predicated,  are  such  as  are  contained  in  the  sub- 
stance of  each  thing,  but  these  are  not  infinite. 
ject  Je  SrS1d"  Both  these  indeed  and  accidents  are  ascending, 
t  i.e.  immedi-  and  both  are  not  infinite,  wherefore  it  is  neces- 
^Asc.  sary  that  there  should  be  something*  of  which 

§  As  b.  primarily  f  something  J  is  predicated,  and  some- 

catt  ^s3  A^^'"    tninS    else  §    °f    tnis>    als°    that    this    Should    Stop, 

ir  Prior  to  b.  and  that  there  should  be  something  II  which  is 
is  nothing  prior  neither  predicated  of  another  prior  thing, %  nor 
to  a.  another  prior  thing  of  it.* 

This  then  is  said  to  be  one  mode  of  demon- 
that amedlate    stration,  but  there  is  another  besides,  if  there  is 
proposition        a  demonstration  of  those  of  which  certain  things 
are  previously  predicated,  but  of  what  there  is 
demonstration,  it  is  not  possible  to  be  better  affected  towards 
them  than  to  know  them,  nor  can  we  know  without  demon- 
stration.2    Still  if  thisf  becomes  known  through 
lionhe  °onc  U     these,!  but  these  we  do  not  know,  nor  are  better 
I  The  pre-        affected  towards  them   than  if  we  knew  them, 
neither  shall  we  obtain  scientific  knowledge  of 
that  which  becomes  known  through  these.     If  then  it  is  pos- 
sible to  know  any  thing  simply  through  demonstration,  and 
s  cf  Prior  An     not  fr°m  certain  things,  nor  from  hypothesis,  §  it 
ii.  ch.  is.  is  necessary   that  the  intermediate  predications 

5.  if  there  is  should  stop  ;  for  if  they  do  not  stop,  but  there  is 
predication,  always  something  above  what  is  assumed,  there 
demonstration        -ii   ^        demonstration  of  all  things,  so  that  if 

cannot  exist.  .  .  in 

we  cannot  pass  through  infinites,  we  shall  not 
know  by  demonstration  those  things  of  which  there  is  de- 
monstration. If  then  we  are  not  better  affected  towards 
them  than  if  we  knew  them,  it  will  be  impossible  to  know 

1  As  whiteness  of  a  swan,  blackness  of  a  crow. 

2  To  first  principles  (indemonstrable)  we  are  better  affected  than  if  we 
knew  them  through  demonstration,  as  was  shown  in  ch.  2. 


CHAP.  XXII.]  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS. 


295 


any  thing  by  demonstration  simply,  but  by  hy-    *  if  the  pro- 

i       •     ^c.  i  positions  arc 

pothesis.*  '  true 

Logically  then  from  these  things  a  person  may 
believe  about  what  has  been  said,  but  analyti-   pTOVed  Analyti- 
cally2 it   is  more  concisely  manifest   thus,  that   caiiy  from  the 

,      J  .....  J  ,.  .       ,  nature  of  those 

there  cannot  be  infinite  predicates  in  clemonstra-    things  which 
tive  sciences,  the  subject  -of  the  present  treatise,   aTeH ,Pr?djcated 
either  in  an  ascending  or  descending  series,    ror 
demonstration  is  of  such  things  as  are  essentially  present  with 
things,  essentially  in  two  ways,  both  such  as  are  in  them  in 
respect  of  what  a  thing  is,  and  those  in  which  the  things 
themselves  are  inherent  in  respect  of  what  a  thing  is,  thus 
the  odd  in  number  which  indeed  is  inherent  in  number,  but 
number  itself  is  inherent  in  the  definition  of  it,f 
again  also,  multitude  or  the  divisible  is  inherent   odd.eofthe 
in   the  definition   of  number.       Still   neither    of 
these  can  be  infinites,  nor  as  the  odd  is  predicated  of  number, 
for  again  there  will  be  something  else  in  the  odd,$   j  e.  g.  inequai- 
in  which  S  bein";  inherent, II  (the  odd)  would  be   »ty-    ,    _,  „  . 

o  <i  /\\    \  /  £  In  the  denni- 

inherent,  and  if  this  be  so,  number  will  be  first  tion  of  which. 

inherent  in  those  things  which  are  inherent  in  it.  jjdd-  e- in  tlle 

If  then  such  infinites  cannot  be  inherent  in  the  f  cf.  Met.  As 

one.^F  neither  will  there  be  infinites  in  ascend-  the  finite  can- 

•  o    -ii     •  l  n        l  1  1      not  contain 

ing  series.     Still  it  is  necessary  that  all  should   infinity. 
be  inherent  in  the  first,*  for  example,  in  number,    *  Thus  .thet 

.        ,  ,  .  i  ■«  •  third  is  in  the 

and  number  m  them,j  so  that  they  will  recipro-   second, and  the 
cate,  but  not  be  more  widely  extensive.     Neither   s^"d  m  thc 
are  those  infinite  which  are  inherent  in  the  defi-   t  in  their  de- 
nition  of  a  thing,:}:  for  if  they  were,  we  could  not   ("ctMetap. 
define,  so  that  if  all  predicates  are  predicated  per   lib- ix-  (*•>• 
se,  and  these  are  not  infinite,  things  in  an  upward  progression 
will  stop,  wherefore  also  those  which  descend. 

1  Jam  si  vera  scientia  demonstratione  comparari  potest,  quae  neces- 
sario  vera  sit,  ut  non  pendeat  ex  aliis  conditionibus  quibuscunque,  quae 
et  esse  possint,  et  non  esse,  terminorum  mediorum,  quibus  demonstratio 
utitur,  numerus  non  erit  inlinitus  :  nam  si  esset,  et  omnia  demonstrari 
possent,  et,  quia  infinitam  demonstrationem  periicere  non  liceret,  quedam 
demonstrari  non  possent,  ut  demonstratio  non  efficeret  veram  scientiam, 
sed  hypotheticam,  h.  e.  non  cogeretur  quod  demonstrator  ex  proposition- 
ibus  certis,  sed  ex  propositionibus  quae,  quamquam  ipsee  demonstrari  de- 
berent,  tamen  pro  certis  sumtae  essent.  Waitz.  By  hypothesis,  he  alludes 
to  what  is  not  self-evidently  certain,  but  is  assumed  to  be  BO. 

2  From  the  principles  and  essence  of  demonstration.    Vide  supra. 


296 


ARISTOTLE  S    ORGANON. 


[BOOK    I. 


6.  That  there 
is  not  infinity 
of  media. 


*  Vide  ch.  3 


If  then  this  be  so,  those  also  which  are  between 
the  two  terms  will  be  always  finite,  but  if  this 
be  the  case,  it  is  cl°ar  now  that  there  must  neces- 
arily  be  principles  of  demonstrations,  and  that  there  is  vn: 
demonstration  of  all  things,  as  we  observed  in  tin 
beginning,*  certain  persons  assert.  For  if  there  be 
principles,  neither  are  all  things  demonstrable,  nor  can  we  pro- 
gress to  infinity,  since  that  either  of  these  should  be,  is  nothing 
else  than  that  there  is  no  proposition  immediate  and  indivisible, 
but  that  all  things  are  divisible,  since  what  is  demonstrated 
+  The  middle.  *s  demonstrated  from  the  term  f  being  inwardly 
introduced,  and  not  from  its  being  (outwardly)  as- 
sumed.]: l  Wherefore  if  this  §  may  possibly  proceed 
to  infinity,  the  media  between  two  terms  ||  might 
also  possibly  be  infinite,  but  this  is  impossible,  if 
i.  e.  between  predications  upwards  and  downwards  stop,  and 
attribute  of  the  that  they  do  stop,  has  been  logically  shown  before, 
first  prop.  an(j  analytically  now. 


X  Extrinsecus 
definitio. 
Buhle. 

§  The  demon- 
stration of  pro 
positions. 


I,  Case  where 
no  common 
ground  of  in- 
herency sub- 
sists. 
11  As  C  of  D. 

•  Some  term 
in  common 
predicated  of  C 
and  D. 

t  Viz.  triangle. 

%  i.  e.  triangle. 

§  Viz.  scalene, 
isosceles,  etc. 


Chap.  XXIII. —  Certain  Corollaries. 

From  what  has  been  shown  it  appears  plain  that 
if  one  and  the  same  thing  is  inherent  in  two,  for 
instance,  A  in  C  and  in  D,  when  one  is  not  pre- 
dicated of  the  other, If  either  not  at  all  or  not  uni- 
versally, then  it  is  not  always  inherent  according 
to  something  common.*  Thus  to  the  isosceles 
and  to  the  scalene  triangle,  the  possession  of  an- 
gles equal  to  two  right,  is  inherent  according  to 
something  common, f  for  it  is  inherent  so  far  as 
each  is  a  certain  figure,]:  and  not  so  far  as  it  is 
something  else.§  This  however  is  not  always  the 
case,  for  let  B  be  that  according  to  which  A  is 


1  Being  assumed  between  the  subject  and  attribute  of  the  prop,  to  be 
proved.  Thus  the  middle  term  is  assumed  in  the  first  figure,  in  which  it 
is  subjected  to  the  attribute,  i.  e.  to  the  greater  extreme,  and  is  attributed 
to  the  subject,  i.  e.  to  the  less  extreme.  Taylor.  By  the  middle  being 
inwardly  introduced,  he  means  that  in  order  to  demonstrate  A  B,  A  must 
be  predicated  of  C,  and  C  of  B,  but  A  of  B,  and  B  of  C.  Upon  the  above 
chap.,  compare  Metap.  lib.  iii.  iv.  vi.  ix.  xiii. ;  Eth.  book  i.  ch.  6;  De 
Amm.  b.  iii.  Vide  also  Hill's  Logic,  de  Definitione,  and  Whately's  Logic, 
b.  h.  ch   5,  and  b.  iii.  sec.  10. 


CHAP.  XXIII.]         THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  297 

inherent  in  C  D.  then  it  is  evident1  that  B  is  also  inherent  in 
C,  and  in   D,  according  to  something  else  com-    .  As  E 
mon  *  and  that  alsot  according  to  something  else.i    t  e  is  -nc 
so  that  between  two  terms. §  infinite  terms  may    t  As  f. 
be   inserted,   but   this  is  impossible. II      It  is  not    §  Viz.  between 

1  !  1     •  1  T    1  1  B   alld   C>    0r   B 

then  necessary  that  the  same  thing  should  always  and  d. 
be  inherent  in  many,  according  to  something  com-  "  A  lde  ch-  22- 
mon,  since  indeed  there  will  be  immediate  propositions  ;  it  is 
moreover  requisite  that  the  terms  should  be  in  the  same  genus, 
and  from  the  same  individuals,  since  that  which  is  common 
will  be  of  those  which  are  essentially  inherent,  for  it  is  im- 
possible to  transfer  things  which  are  demonstrated 

J.  .?        «-  H  Vide  ch.  6. 

irom  one  genus  to  another.! 

But  it  is  also  manifest  that  when  A  is  with  B,    2  Cases  of 
if  there  is  a  certain  middle,  we  may  show  that  B   positional  de- 
is  with  A,  and  the  elements  of  this*  are  these  and   wnen  a certain 
whatever  are  media,  for  immediate  propositions,   "j.!^1,""1  Is 
either  all  of  them,  or  those  which  are  universal,    •  oi  the  con- 
are  elements.2     Yet  if  there  is  not  (a  medium)   clusion  B  is  A- 
there  is  no  longer  demonstration,  but  this  is  the  way  to  prin- 
ciples.!    In  like  manner,  if  A  is  not  with  B,  if  +  To  first  prin. 
there  is  either  a  middle,  or  something  prior  to   cipies. 
which  it  |  is  not  present, §  there  is  a  dcmonstra-    +  soWaitzar.i 
tion,3  but  if  not,  there  is  no  demonstration,  but  a   ?e£ker- 
principle,    and    there   are   as  many   elements   as 
terms, ||  for  the  propositions  of  these  are  the  prin-    "  VithB. 
cipies  of  demonstration.     As  also  there  are  certain  indemon 
strable  principles,  that  this  is  that,  and  that  this  is  present  with 
that,  so  there  are  also  that  this  is  not  that,  and  that  this  is  not 

1  Because  if  a  thing  is  inherent  in  two  things,  it  is  inherent  mediately. 
Taylor. 

2  Immediate  particular  propositions  are  not  the  principles  of  demon- 
strations, but  of  inductions.  Upon  the  use  of  the  word  oroix^a,  by  Aris- 
totle, cf.  Ammonius  upon  Catego.  ch.  12;  also  Biese  i.  p.  381,  note  5, 
Trendelenburg  Platonis  de  Ideis.  In  the  Topics,  as  Waitz  observes,  he 
uses  aroixt'ia  as  synonymous  with  to7toi,  for  certain  universal  arguments, 
from  which,  with  some  appearance  of  truth,  a  thing  may  be  either  proved 
or  refuted.  Top.  lib.  iv.  ch.  1,  etc.  The  sense  here,  of  elements,  seems 
most  suggestive  of  their  meaning,  viz.  that  of  certain  principles  of  dis- 
putation, which  when  provided,  enable  us  rightly  to  conduct  an  argument. 

3  If  there  is  a  certain  middle  (C)  through  which  A  is  proved  not  pre- 
sent with  B,  A  will  iirst  be  denied  of  C  in  the  major  premise,  and  alter* 
wards  of  B  in  the  conclusion;  thus  a  syllogism  will  result  in  Cclareiil : 
No  C  is  A,  every  B  is  C ;  therefore  no  B  is  A. 


298  aristotle's  organox.  [book  & 

present  with  that,  so  that  there  will  be  some  principles  that  a 
thing  is,  hut  others  that  it  is  not.    Still  when  it  is  required  to 

*  As  that  a  is  demonstrate,*  that  which  is  first  predicated  of  B 
with  b.  must  be  assumed ;  let  this  be  C,  and  let  A,  in  like 
ifn  bSES™  manner»  (be  predicated)  of  this  ;  f  by  always  pro- 
t  The  middle  ceeding  thus> '  there  is  never  a  proposition  ex- 
d.  ternally,  nor  is  that  J  which  is  present  with  A 
assumed  in  the  demonstration,  but  the  middle  is  always  con- 
3.  what  posi-  Sensed  till  they  become  indivisible  and  one.2  They 
tion  the  con-      are  one  indeed  when  the  immediate  is  produced. 

necting  term  j  .  •  i, 

should  occupy    and  one  proposition  simply,  an  immediate  one, 

uvewd  ™£-  an.d  as  in  other  things  the  principle  is  simple,  but 
tiveproposi-  this  is  not  the  same  every  where,  but  in  weight 
it  is  a  minor,  in  melody  a  demi-semi-quaver,3  and 
something  else  in  another  thing,  thus  in  syllogism,  "the  one" 
is  an  immediate  proposition,  but  in  demonstration  and  science 
§  Cf.  An.  Post.  Jt  is  intuition. §4  In  syllogisms  then,  which  de- 
ii.  ch.  19,  and  monstrate  the  being  inherent,  nothing  falls  beyond 
l,  2,"  ands."  '  (the  middle),  but  in  negatives  here,||  nothing  falls 
•Ir  s^u  medium  external  of  that  which  ought  to  be  inherent,5^  as 
non  sumitur  if  A  is  not  present  with  B  through  C.  For  if  C 
Buhie.U,n;       ■  Is  present  with  every  B,*  but  A  with  no  C,f  and 

*  The  minor  if,  again,  it  should  be  requisite  to  show  that  A  is 
trThe major,      "with  no  C,|  we  must  assume  the  medium  of  A 

*  The  conclu-     and  C,  and  thus  we  must  always  proceed.6     If 

1  By  assuming  a  new  term,  as  predicate  of  the  minor,  and  subject  of 
the  major. 

3  Until  we  arrive  at  an  indemonstrable  and  immediate  proposition. 

3  Aiearig.  The  least  perceptible  sound  we  have  therefore  expressed  it ; 
by  its  closest  representative  in  music. 

4  For  we  know  principles  by  "  vovg."  Cf.  de  Anim.  iii.  ch.  4—6,  ubi 
cf.  Trende.,  Biese.  and  Rassow.  I  have  translated  the  word  "  intuition," 
agreeing  as  I  do  with  Professor  Browne,  (vide  Ethics,  b.  vi.  ch.  6,  Bohn's 
edition,)  that  no  other  word  conveys  with  the  same  exactitude  Aris- 
totle's own  definition  of  it  in  the  Magna  Moralia  (i.  35),  'O  vovq  lari 
irspi  Tag  cipxaq  twv  votjtujv  icai  tuiv  ovtwv,  »;  fiev  yap  iiriarrj/in  raiv  fttr 
a.TroSti^iu>Q  ovTixii'  iariv,  apa  S'  ap\ai  avanooiiKToi. 

5  Thus  Waitz,  Buhle,  and  Bekker.  Taylor  evidently  reads,  o,  Sh,  //?/ 
virapxiiv,  an  amendment  which  Waitz  approves  in  his  note,  and  so  do  I, 
for  the  conclusion  of  the  syllogism  is  of  course  negative;  the  meaning  is, 
that  a  middle  term  is  never  assumed,  which  is  predicated  of  the  major 
extreme,  since  the  major  is  that  in  which  the  conclusion  is  negatively 
predicated  of  the  minor. 

b  Assume  a  middle  term  which  does  not  fall  externally  to  the  major 
extreme,  in  order  to  demonstrate  the  negative  proposition. 


CHAP.  XXIV.]         THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  299 

however  it  should  be  required  to  show*  that  D  is  sion  of  the  pro- 
not  with  E,  because  C  is  with  every  D,f  but  with  *yin°camestres. 
no,  or  not  with  every  E.t  the  medium  will  never   f  £he  major. 

,.  ,,  ,  -r<  i     i  •     p    •  -i         i         •  n     t  Tne  minor. 

tall  external  to  E,  and  tins  §  is  with  what  it  need  §  e. 

not  be  present.1      As  to  the  third  mode,|  it  will  II  The  3rd 

never  proceed  external  to  that  from  which,  nor  gure" 
which  it  is  necessary  to  deny.2 

Chap.  XXIV. —  The  superiority  of  Universal  to  Particular 
Demonstration  proved. 

As  one  demonstration  is  universal,  but  another  1.  The  ques- 
particular,  one  also  affirmative,  but  the  other  ne-  tlon  stated- 
gative,  it  is  questioned  which  is  preferable,  likewise  also 
about  what  is  called  direct  demonstration,  and  that  which 
leads  to  the  impossible.  Let  us  first  then  consider  the  uni- 
versal and  the  particular,  and  having  explained  this,  speak  of 
what  is  called  direct  demonstration,  and  that  to  the  impossible. 

Perhaps  then  to  some  considering  the  matter   2.  Reasons 
in  this  way,  the  particular  may  appear  the  better,    **y  particular 

Qcnioiist  rstion 

for  if  that  demonstration  is  preferable,  by  which  may  appear 
we  obtain  better  knowledge,  for  this  is  the  excel-  el,£lble- 
lence  of  demonstration,  but  we  know  each  thing  better  when 
we  know  it  per  se,  than  when  through  something  else,  (as  we 
know  Coriscus  is  a  musician,  when  we  know  that  Coriscus  is 
a  musician  rather  than  when  we  know  that  a  man  is  a  musi- 
cian, and  likewise  in  other  things,)  but  the  universal  demon- 
strates because  a  tiling  is  something  else,  not  because  it  is  that 
which  it  is,  as  that  an  isosceles  triangle  (has  two  right  angles), 
not  because  it  is  isosceles,  but  because  it  is  a  triangle,)  but  the 
particular  demonstrates  because  a  thing  is  what  it  is,  if  then 
the  demonstration  per  se  is  preferable,  and  the  particular  is 
such  rather  than  the  universal,  particular  demonstration  would 
be  the  better.     Besides,  if  the  universal  is  nothing  else  than 

1  It  is  the  subject  of  the  negative  conclusion,  of  which  D  is  denied. 

2  A  middle  will  never  be  assumed  ahove  the  greater  or  less  extreme, 
nor  be  predicated  of  either,  because  in  the  3rd  figure  the  middle  term  is 
always  the  subject  of  both  premises.  As  Taylor  remarks,  in  the  whole 
of  this  chapter,  the  middle  is  said  to  fall  external  to  the  extreme,  when  it 
changes  its  situation  ;  so  that  if  it  was  before  the  subject  of  the  major 
extreme,  afterwards  in  the  pro-syllogism,  it  becomes  the  predicate  of  the 
major. 


300  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

t  particulars,  but  demonstration  produces  opinion 

that  this  thing  is  something  according  to  which  it 
demonstrates,  and  that  a  certain  nature  of  this  kind  is  in 
things  which  subsist,  (as  of  triangle  besides  particular  (tri- 
angles), and  of  figure  besides  particular  (figures),  and  of  num- 
ber besides  particular  (numbers),  but  the  demonstration  about 
being  is  better  than  that  about  non-being,  and  that  through 
which  there  is  no  deception  than  that  through  which  there  is, 
but  universal  demonstration  is  of  this  sort,  (since  men  pro- 
ceeding demonstrate  as  about  the  analogous,1  as  that  a  thing 
which  is  of  such  a  kind  as  to  be  neither  line  nor  number,  nor 
solid  nor  superficies,  but  something  besides  these,  is  analo- 
gous,) if  then  this  is  more  universal,  but  is  less  conversant 
with  being  than  particular,  and  produces  false  opinion,  uni- 
versal will  be  inferior  to  particular  demonstration. 
■  i.  e.  the  first.  First  then  may  we  not  remark  that  one  of  these 
3  Reply  to  the  arguments  *  does  not  apply  more  to  universal  than 
to  particular  demonstration  ?  For  if  the  possession 
of  angles  equal  to  two  right  angles  is  inherent,  not  in  respect 
of  isosceles,  but  of  triangle,  whoever  knows  that  it  is  isosceles 
knows  less  essentially2  than  he  who  knows  that  it  is  triangle. 
In  short,  if  not  so  far  as  it  is  triangle,  he  then  shows  it,  there  will 
+  Supply— in-  not  °*e  demonstration,  but  if  it  is,f  whoever  knows 
herent.orisde-   a  thing  so  far  as  it  is  what  it  is,  knows  that  thins: 

monstrated  so  ,        x/>    . ,  .    .         ,       .         „       .  ,  .    ° 

far  as  it  is  tri-  more.*  It  then  triangle  is  of  wider  extension 
ricfthat  all  (than  isosceles),  and  there  is  the  same  definition,! 
species  of  it  are  and  triangle  is  not  equivocal,  and  the  possession 
caUed^angie.  °^  tw0  angles  equal  to  two  right  angles  is  inhe- 
rent in  every  triangle,  triangle  will  have  such 
angles,  not  so  far  as  it  is  isosceles,  but  the  isosceles  will  have 
them,  so  far  as  it  is  triangle.     Hence  he  who  knows  the  uni- 

1  They  who  employ  universal  demonstration  do  not  keep  within  the 
exact  limits  of  demonstration,  but  appear  to  go  beyond  them  in  the  same 
way  as  those  who  reason  Ik  tov  dvd  \6yov,  for  if  they  have  demon- 
strated any  thing  of  lines,  body,  etc.,  they  apply  the  proof  as  equally  con- 
clusive to  every  thing  similar,  and  thus  extend  the  demonstration  unfairly. 

2  Minus  scit  quatenus  ipsum  (tale  est  ut  habere  duos  rectos  angulos 
illi  insit).    Buhle. 

3  As  Mansel  observes,  (Appendix,  note  B,)  the  office  of  logic  is  to 
contribute  to  the  distinctness  of  a  conception,  by  an  analysis  and  separate 
exposition  of  the  different  parts  contained  within  it.  The  mind,  like  the 
sky,  has  its  nebula?,  which  the  telescope  of  logic  may  resolve  into  their 
component  stars. 


CHAP.  XXIV.]        THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  301 

versal,  knows  more  in  regard  to  the  being  inherent  than  he  who 
knows  particularly,  hence  too  the  universal  is  better  than  the 
particular  demonstration.     Moreover  if  there  is  one  certain 
definition,  and  no  equivocation,  the  universal  will 
not  subsist  less,  but  rather  more  than  certain  par- 
ticulars, inasmuch  as  in  the  former  there  are  things  incorrupt- 
ible, but  particulars  are  more  corruptible.1     Besides,  there  is 
no  necessity  that  wre  should  apprehend  this  (universal)  to  be 
something  besides  these  (particulars),  because  it  shows  one 
thing,  no  more  than  in  others  which  do  not  signify  substance, 
but  quality,  or  relation,  or  action,  but  if  a  person  thinks  thus, 
it  is  the  hearer,  and  not  demonstration,  which  is  to  blame.2 
Again,  if  demonstration  is  a  syllogism,  showing       universal 
the  cause  and  the  why,  the  universal  indeed  is   aione  is  cogni- 
rather  causal,  for  that  with  which  any  thing  is    ^Therefore6' 
essentially  present,  is  itself  a  cause  to  itself,*  but   n,lore  causal, 
the  universal  is  the  first, f  therefore  the  universal   5 ;  Eth.  vi.  3. 
is  cause.     Wherefore  the  (universal)  demonstra-   i^'in^iiich'a 
tion  is  better,  since  it  rather  partakes  of  the  cause   property  is  per 
and  the  why,  besides  up  to  this  we  investigate  the   se  m  erent' 
why,  and  we  think  that  then  we  know  it,  when  this  is  be- 
coming, or  is,  not  because  something  else  (is),  for  thus  there 
is  the  end  and  the  last  boundary.     For  example,  on  what  ac- 
count did  he  come  ?  that  he  might  receive  money,  but  this  that 
he  might  pay  his  debts,  this  that  he  might  not  act  unjustly, 
and  thus  proceeding,  when  it  is  no  longer  on  account  of  some- 
thing else,  nor  for  the  sake  of  another  thing,  then  we  say  that 
he  came,  and  that  it  is,  and  that  it  becomes  on  account  of  this 
as  the  end,  and  that  then  we  especially  know  why  he  came. 
If  then  the  same  occurs,  as  to  all  causes  and  inquiries  into  the 
why,  but  as  to  things  which  are  so  causes  as  that  for  the  sake 

1  So  Waitz,  who  has  this  note,  "  Notiones  universales,  si  unitatem 
quandam  exprimunt  et  si  alius  earum  est  usus  quam  ut  orationem  am- 
biguam  faciant,  quum  singula  quae  illis  subjecta  sint  pereant,  illse  yero 
non  corrumpantur,  etiam  rectius  ipsac  existero  dicentur  quam  ra  dro/ia." 
Cf.  Metap.  lib.  ii.  (iii.),  v.  (vi.),  vi.  (vii.),  ix.  (x.),and  xi.  (xii.),  Leipsic ; 
Phys.  lib.  iii.  and  viii. ;  also  Crakanthorpe's  Logic,  lib.  ii.,  and  upon  this 
chapter  generally,  Aquinas  in  Periherm.  sect.  i. 

2  That  is,  if  a  man  thinks  that  universal  is  something  besides  particu- 
lars. By  universal  here,  he  means,  that  which  is  "  co-ordinated  "  with 
the  many,  and  which  when  abstracted  out  of  the  many  by  the  mir.U, 
produces  the  universal,  which  is  of  posterior  origin.    Taylor. 


S02  Aristotle's  organox.  "book  i. 

*  (AHquid  sit  of  which,*  we  thus  especially  know,  in  other 
BuWet-)  things  also  we  then  chiefly  know,  when  this  no 

longer  subsists  because  another  thing  does.1  When 
therefore  we  know  that  the  external  angles  are  equal  to  four 
right  angles,  because  it  is  isosceles,  the  inquiry  yet  remains, 
why  because  isosceles,  because  it  is  a  triangle,  and  this  be- 
cause it  is  a  rectilinear  figure.  But  if  it  is  this  no  longer  on 
account  of  something  else,  then  we  pre-eminently  know,  then 

also  universally,  wherefore  the  universal  is  better. 
"noVper"6  Again,  by  how  much  more  things  are  according 
aiiud,"but         to  the  particular,  do  they  fall  into  infinites,  but 

the  universal  tends  to  the  simple  and  the  finite, 
so  far  indeed  as  they  are  infinite,  they  are  not  subjects  of 
science,  but  so  far  as  they  are  finite  they  may  be  known, 
wherefore  so  far  as  they  are  universal,  are  they  more  objects 

of  scientific  knowledge,  than  so  far  as  they  are 

?"„YIi",l?rsa-l  particular.  Universals  however  are  more  demon- 
tend  totnesim-    r  m 

pie  and  finite,  strable,  and  of  things  more  demonstrable  is  there 

m"reescientific.  pre-eminent  demonstration,   for  relatives  are  at 

t  i.  e.  if  one  is  one  an(l  the  same  time  more,f  whence  the  uni- 

more,  the  other  Versal  is  better,  since  it  is  demonstration  pre- 

is  more.  .  ,         _      ;  -  ,  .  r 

eminently.  Besides,  that  demonstration  is  prefer- 
able, according  to  which  this  and  something  else  are  known, 
to  that,  by  which  this  alone  is  known,  now  he  who  has  the  uni- 
versal knows  also  the  particular,  but  the  latter  does  not  know 
the  universal,  wherefore  even  thus  the  universal  will  be  more 

eligible.  Again,  as  follows  :  it  is  possible  rather 
closer  in  de-  to  demonstrate  the  universal,  because  a  person 
thenprinciXt0    demonstrates  through  a  medium  which  is  nearer 

to  the  principle,  but  what  is  immediate  is  the 
nearest  and  this  is  the  principle ;  if  then  that  demonstration 
which  is  from  the  principle  is  more  accurate  than  that  which 
is  not  from  the  principle,  the  demonstration  which  is  in  a 
greater  degree  from  the  principle,  is  more  accurate  than  that 
which  is  from  it  in  a  less  degree.  Now  the  more  universal  is 
of  this  kind,  wherefore  the  universal  will  be  the  better,  as  if 
it  were  required  to  demonstrate  A  of  D,  and  the  media  should 
be  B   C,   but    B   the   higher    wherefore   the   demonstration 


c 


through  this  is  more  universal. 


"O 


1  A  verbose  exemplification  of  the  terse  truism  of  Swift,  that  "  we  un- 
ravel sciences,  as  we  do  old  stockings,  by  beginning  at  the  foot." 


CHAP.  XXV.]  THE    POSTERIOR    4.XALYriCS. 


303 


Some  of  the  above  arguments  are  logical,  it  is 
chiefly  clear  however  that  the  universal  is  more 
excellent,  because  when  of  two  propositions  we 
have  that  which  is  the  prior,*  we  also  in  a  certain 
degree  know  and  possess  in  capacity  that  which 
is  posterior  ;  thus  if  a  man  knows  that  every  tri- 
angle has  angles  equal  to  two  right,  he  also  in  a 
certain  respect  knows  in  capacity  that  an  isosceles 
triangle  has  angles  equal  to  two  right,  even  if 
know  that  the  isosceles  is  a  triangle,"]"  but  he  who 
has  this  proposition  by  no  means  knows  the  uni- 
versal, neither  in  capacity  nor  in  energy.  The 
universal  proposition  also  is  intuitively  intelligible, 
but  the  particular  ends  in  sense.1  J 


7.  The  uni- 
versal is  above 
all  superior,  in 
that  it  compre- 
hends the  par- 
ticular, and  is 
more  intel- 
lectual. 
*  The  uni- 
versal proposi- 
tion. 

he  does  not 

t  The  particu- 
lar proposition. 


t  An.  Post   ii. 
ch.  19. 


Chap.  XXV. —  TJte  Superiority  of  Affirmative  to  Negative 
Demonstration  proved. 

That  universal  is  better  than  particular  demon-  j  That  the  de- 

stration,  let  so  much  be  alleged,  but  that  the  af-  monstration 

firmative  is  preferable  to  the  negative,  will  be  through" fewer 

evident  from   this.      Let  that  demonstration  be  postulates, etc., 

,  .  -,  p        i  •    i  •  e   c  is,  "caetens  pa- 

better,  castens  paribus,  §  which  consists  ot  iewer   ribus,"  the  bet- 
postulates,  or  hypotheses,  or  propositions.     For  if  ex'arifpTel^'nd5' 
they2   are   similarly   known,  quicker   knowledge   applied  to  af- 
will  be  obtained  through  these,  which  is  more    §Asitmaybe 
eligible.    The  reason  however  of  this  proposition,    from  unknown 
that  that  which  consists  of  fewer  is  better,  uni- 
versally is  this ;   for  if  the  media  are  similarly  known,  but 
things  prior  are  more  known,  let  the  demonstration  be  through 
the  media  of  B  C  D,  that  A  is  present  with  E,  but  through 
F  G,  that  A  is  present  with  E.3  That  A  is  present  with  D,  and 
that  A  is  present  with  E  subsists  similarly,!  but    y  Each  is  the 
that  A  is  with  D,  is  prior  and  more  known  than    conclusion. 
that   A   is   with   E,    for   that  if  is   demonstrated    it  viz.  a  e. 

1  Cf.  de  An.  iii.  6  ;  Metaph.  ix.  1 ;  and  upon  the  conception  of  uni- 
versal notions,  Reid's  Works,  Hamilton's  ed. ;  Mill's  Logic;  Whately's 
Rhet. ;  Trende.  Biese  i.  p.  327,  note  4;   Rassow,  p.  72. 

1  Viz.  the  propositions  of  both  demonstrations. 

3  B  C  and  F  G  are  the  same,  but  they  are  called  B  C,  so  far  as  they 
form  parts  of  the  syllogism  concluding  A  E  ;  and  they  are  called  V  li,  so 
far  as  they  belong  to  the  syllogisir   I  D. 


304 


ARISTOTLE  S    OKGANON. 


[book 


•  s.  e.  A  D. 


+  i.  e.  both  af- 
firmatives and 
negatives. 
X  Affirmative. 


2.  The  nega- 
tive requires 
the  affirmative, 
but  the  latter 
does  not  need 
the  former. 
§  Vide  Pr.  An. 
i.  ch.  7  and  24. 
||  That  nega- 
tion is  proved 
by  affirmation. 
IT  By  pro-syllo- 
gisms. 


through  this,*  and  that  is  more  credible  through 
which  (a  thing  is  demonstrated).  Also  the  de- 
monstration which  is  through  fewer  things  is  therefore  better, 
ceteris  paribus ;  both  f  then  are  demonstrated 
through  three  terms,  and  two  propositions,  but 
the  one  assumes  that  something  is,J  and  the  other, 
that  something  is  and  is  not,1  hence  through  a 
greater  number  of  things  (the  demonstration  is  made)  so  that 
it  is  the  worse. 

Moreover  since  it  has  been  shown  impossible 
for  a  syllogism  to  be  produced  with  both  propo- 
sitions negative,§  but  that  one  must  of  necessity 
be  such  (negative),  and  the  other  that  a  thing  is 
present  with,  (that  is  affirmative,)  we  must  in  ad- 
dition to  this  assume  this, [|  for  it  is  necessary  that 
affirmative  (propositions)  when  the  demonstration 
is  increased,^  should  become  more,  but  it  is  im- 
possible that  the  negatives  should  be  more  than 
one  in  every  syllogism.  For  let  A  be  present  with  nothing 
of  those  with  which  B  is,  but  B  be  present  with  every  C,  if 
indeed,  again,  it  should  be  necessary  to  increase  both  propo- 
*  To  prove  sitions,*  a  middle  must  be  introduced.2  Of  A  B 
them  by  pro-  ti,en  iet  tne  middle  be  D,  but  of  B  C  let  the  mid- 
die  be  E,  E  then  is  evidently  affirmative,-!-  but  D 
firmed  of  E,and  is  affirmative  indeed  of  B,  yet  is  placed  negatively 
E  of  c-  as  regards  A,  since  it  is  necessary  that  D  should 

be  present  with  every  B,  but  A  with  no  D  ;  there  is  then  one 
negative  proposition,  viz.  A  D.J  The  same  mode 
also  subsists  in  other  syllogisms,  for  the  middle 
of  affirmative  terms  is  always  affirmative  in  re- 
spect of  both  (extremes),  §  but  in  the  case  of  a 
negative  (syllogism),  the  middle  must  be  neces- 
sarily negative  in  respect  to  one  of  the  two,||  so 
there  is  one  proposition  of  this  kind,^[  but  the 
others  are  affirmative.  If  then  that  is  more  known 
and  credible  through  which  a  thing  is  demon- 
strated, but  the  negative  is  shown  through  the 


X  The  major. 


§  Subject  of 
the  major,  and 
predicate  of  the 
minor — both 
affirmatively. 
||  Of  the  major 
extreme  to 
which  it  is  sub- 
ject in  the 
T>:ajor  prem. 
*fi  The  major  is 
negative. 


1  Because  of  negative  demonstration,  one  premise  affirms,  but  the  other 
denies. 

2  This  is  done  when  a  pro-syllogism  is  constructed  in  the  1st  figure, 
because  here  alone  the  middle  term  occupies  the  middle  place.  . 


CHAP.  XXVI.]  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  305 

affirmative,  and  the  latter  not  through  the  former,  this,  since 
it  is  prior,  more  known,  and  more  credible,  will  be  better. 
Again,  since  the  principle  of  syllogism  is  an  universal  imme- 
diate proposition,  but  the  universal  proposition  in  an  ostensive 
(demonstration)  is  affirmative,  but  in  a  negative  is  negative, 
and  since  the  affirmative  is  prior  to,  and  more  known  than,  the 
negative,  for  negation  is  known  through  affirmation,  and  at' 
tirmation  is  prior,  just  as  being  is  prior  to  not  be-  3.  Affirmative 
ing,  therefore  the  principle  of  affirmative  is  better   comes  nearer 

.,  1  f  •  1  -i  t  tnan  negative 

than   that   or   negative   demonstration,    but    that  to  the  nature  of 

which  uses  better  principles  is  better.     Moreover  aPnnciPle- 

it   partakes    more   of  the    nature  of   principle,*  *  upxoedca- 

since   without   affirmative   there   is   no   negative  T£pa' 
demonstration.1 

Chap.  XXVI. —  The  Superiority  of  the  same  to  Demonstration 
ad  impossibile  proved." 

Since   affirmative   is    better    than    negative   de-    1.  Thediffer- 
monstration,  it  is  evidently  also  better  than  that   exan$e7be-  y 
which  leads  to  the  impossible,!  it  is  necessary   *ween  direct 

1  '.'  J      demonstration 

however  to    know   what   the  difference  between    and  that  which 
them  is.     Let  A  then  be  present  with  no  B,  but   sUarcdsum^  ab" 
let  B  be  with  every  C,  wherefore  it  is  necessary   t  vide  infra. 
that  A  should   be  with  no  C,  (the  terms)  then  being  thus  as- 
sumed, the  negative  proposition  proving  that  A  is  not  present 
with  C  will  be  ostensive.     The  demonstration  however  to  the 
impossible  is  as  follows  :  if  it  is  required  to  show  that  A  is  not 
present  with  B  it  must  be  assumed  present,;}:  also    j  in  order  to  a 
that  B  is  with  C  so  that  it  will  happen  that  A  is    right  syllogism 
with   C.     Let  this  however  be  known   and  ac-   '"  b    lgulc 
knowledged  impossible,  then  it  is  impossible  that  A  should  be 
with  B ;  if  then  B  is  acknowledged  present  with  C,  it  is  im- 

1  An  affirmative  partakes  more  of  the  nature  of  principle  than  a  nega- 
tive demonstration,  because  the  minor  prem.  of  a  negat.  is  proved  through 
an  affirmative. 

2  Vide  Hill's  and  Mansel's  Logic,  article  Demonstration  ;  alsoWhately, 
App.  I.  xi.,  upon  "Impossibility,"  and  Rhetoric,  part  i.  ch.  3,  see.  7. 
The  tig  to  afiovarov  dyovaa  anofittZtg  here,  seems  to  correspond  with 
the  tXtyriKov  ivOvprifia  of  the  Rhetoric,  upon  which  sec  Dr.  Hessey's 
Schera.  Khet.  Table  4.  CI',  also  Anal.  Pr.  1.  22  and  38;  Khet.  ti.  22—24 
and  30  ;  iii.  17,  13. 

T 


306  Aristotle's  okganox.  [book  i. 

possible  that  A  should  be  with  B.     The  terms  then  indeed 

*  in  theosten-   are  similarly  arranged,*  but  it  makes  a  difference 

she  as  in  the     which  negative  proposition  is  more  known,  viz. 

impossi  i  e.   wjietjier  tjiat  ^  js  not  presenj;  -vvith  B,  or  that  A 

is  not  present  with  C.  When  then  the  conclusion  is  more 
known  that  it  is  not,  there  is  a  demonstration  to  the  impos- 
t  The  negation  si°le  produced,  but  when  that  which  f  is  in  the 
that  a  is  not  syllogism  (is  more  known)  the  demonstration  is 
ostensive.  Naturally,  however,  that  A  is  not  pre- 
sent with  B  is  prior  to  A  is  not  present  with  C,  for  those 
things  are  prior  to  the  conclusion,  from  which  the  conclusion 
(is  collected),  and  that  A  is  not  with  C  is  the  conclusion,  but 
that  A  is  not  with  B  is  that  from  which  the  conclusion  is  de- 
rived. For  neither  if  a  certain  thing  happens  to  be  subverted, 
is  this  the  conclusion,  but  those  (the  premises)  from  which 
(the  conclusion  is  derived).  That  indeed  from  which  (it  is 
on-  ro  osi  m^erred)  ls  a  syllogism,  which  may  so  subsist  as 
tion"is  tPor°theS1  either  J  a  whole  to  a  part,  or  as  a  part  to  a 
tohapSnhe!e  whole>§  b.ut  the  propositions  A  C  and  A  B  do  not 
the  major  as  to  thus  subsist  with  regard  to  each  other.  If  then 
§  A™'™ major  tnat  demonstration  which  is  from  things  more 
f  s'ai™  f'd  known  and  prior  be  superior,  but  both  are  credi- 
monstrative        ble  from  something  not  existing,  yet  the  one  from 

iTlKa-  the  Prior'  the  other  from  what  is" posterior,  nega- 
tive.   2nd,        tive  demonstration  will  in  short  be  better,  than 

Adgabsurdum.'  taat  to  the  impossible,  so  that  as  affirmative  de- 
ll Than  nega-  monstration  is  better  than  this,||  it  is  also  evidently 
tive-  better  than  that  leading  to  the  impossible. 

Chap.  XXVII. —  Upon  the  Nature  of  more  Accurate  Science} 

l.  That  one  sci-  One  science  is  more  accurate  than,  and  prior  to, 
subtieSa™drac-  anotnei'>  both  the  science  that  a  tiling  is,  and  the 
curate  than  same  why  it  is,  but  not  separately  that  it  is,  than 
the  science  of  why  it  is,  also  that  which  is  not  of 
a  subject2  than  that  which  is  of  a  subject,  for  instance,  arith- 

1  Cf.  ch.  13;  Plato,  Phileb. ;  Rhet.  b.  i.  ch.  7.  In  the  last  place,  he 
says  that  the  precedence  of  one  science  over  another  is  dependent  upon 
the  higher  elevation  of  its  subject  matter.     Met.  lib.  i.  and  x. 

2  Not  conversant  with  a  material  subject,  as  arithmetic,  which  is  con- 
versant with  number.    Taylor. 


CHAP.  XXVIII.  XXIX.]     THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  307 

metic  then  harmonic  science,  and  that  which  consists  of  fewer 
things  than  that  which  is  from  addition,  as  arithmetic  than 
geometry.  I  mean  by  "  from  addition,"  as  unity  is  a  sub- 
stance without  position,  but  a  point  is  substance  with  posi- 
tion,1 this  is  from  addition. 


Chap.  XXVIII. —  What  constitutes  one,  and  what  different 

Sciences. 

One  science  is  that  which  is  of  one  genus  of  those  1.  whatever 

things  which  are  composed  of  first  (principles),  min!tratlddC" 

and  are  the  parts  or  affections  of  these  per  se;2  from  principles 

,  .*.,.«.  n  ,-t  i  of  a  common 

but  a  science   is   different   trom   another,  whose  genus,  these 

principles  are  neither  from  the  same  things,  nor  ^„£^™ 

one  from  the  other.3     A  token  of  this  is  when  ture  of  diverse 

any  one  arrives  at  things  indemonstrable,  for  it  is  sciences- 

necessary*  that  they  should  be  in  the  same  genus  *  if  it  is  one 

with  those  that  are  demonstrated ;    it  is  also  a  science- 
sign  of  this  when  things  demonstrated  through  them  are  in 
the  same  genus  and  are  cognate. 


Chaf.  XXIX. — That  there  may  be  several  Demonstrations  of  the 

same  thing. 

There  may  possibly  be  many  demonstrations  of  J^^mon- 
the  same  thing,  not  only  when  one  assumes  an   strabie  in  many 

1  A  point  was  defined  by  the  Pythagoreans,  unity  with  position  :  ct*. 
Categ.  ch.  6 ;  Procl.  in  Euc.  Elem.  lib.  ii.  Oso-tv  txliv  dicuntur  ea 
quorum  partes  simul  intuemur  ac  si  oculis  subjectae  essent;  quae  dum 
fluunt,  manent  et  quorum  quasi  imagines  ita  animo  representantur,  ut 
qua?  praeterierint  mente  repeti  possint  simul  cum  iis,  quae  praesto  suit. 
Waitz,  in  Cat.  cap.  6. 

8  Thus  natural  productions,  though  they  possess  their  own  propel 
principles,  are  ultimately  composed  of  the  first  and  common  principles, 
matter  and  form  :  these  last  constitute  the  parts  of  body,  but  body  and 
soul  the  parts  of  animal.  Also  in  the  sciences  we  must  consider  the  sub- 
jects of  them,  their  parts,  and  their  proper  affections. 

J  Thai  is,  their  principles  neither  issue  from  a  common  source,  nor  are 
so  intermingled  that  the  one  may  be  derived  from  the  other:  thus  phy- 
sics and  arithmetic  are  different  sciences,  but  the  science  of  motion  and 
of  the  heavens  are  not  entirely  different    Vide  Physics. 

x   2 


308  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

modes,  both  un-continued  medium  from  the  same  class,*  as  if 
when  the  raid-  q  j)  an(j  jo  (were  assumed)  of  A  B,  j"  but  also  from 
fmmX^ame,  another  (series).1  Thus,  let  A  be  to  be  changed, 
ferentVnuf  D  to  be  movedJ  B  to  be  delighted,  and  again  G 
*  when  one  is  to  be  tranquillized.  It  is  true  then  to  predicate 
the  other.10  D  of  B  and  A  of  D,  for  whoever  is  delighted  is 
t  The  concin-    moved,  and  what  is  moved  is  changed :  again,  it  is 

true  to  predicate  A  of  G,  and  G  of  B,  for  every 
one  who  is  delighted  is  tranquillized,  and  he  who  is  tran- 
quillized is  changed.  Wherefore  there  is  a  syllogism  through 
different  media,2  and  not  from  the  same  class,  yet  not  so  that 

neither  is  predicated  of  neither  medium,  since  it 

I  DandG.  -g  necessary  that  both  it  should  be  present  with 
§  b.  something  §  which  is  the  same.     We  must  also 

II  Through  how  consider  in  how  many  ways||  there  may  be  a  syl- 
many  media.      i0a-ism  of  the  same  thing  through  the  other  figures. 

Chap.  XXX. — That  there  is  no  Science  of  the  Fortuitous.3 

1.  This  class  There  is  no  science  through  demonstration  of 
does  not  come  tjiat  which  is  fortuitous,  since  the  fortuitous  is 
pur  subjects10!-  neither  as  necessary  nor  as  for  the  most  part,  but 
demonstration.  tnat  wnicn  is  produced  besides  these,  and  demon- 
stration is  of  one  of  these.  For  every  syllogism  is  through 
premises,  either  necessary,  or  through  those  which  are  for  the 
most  part  (true),  and  if  indeed  the  propositions  are  necessary, 
the  conclusion  also  is  necessary  ;  but  if  for  the  most  part 
(true),  the  conclusion  also  is  of  the  same  character.  Hence 
if  the  fortuitous  is  neither  as  for  the  most  part  nor  necessary, 
there  cannot  be  demonstration  of  it. 

n  Vide  Ethics,  Chap.  XXXI. —  That  toe  do  not  possess  Scientific 
b.  vi.  ch.  2  Knowledge  through  Sensation.^ 

and  3. 

i.  The  percep-  Neither  is  it  possible  to  have  scientific  know- 
tion  of  the         led"-e  through   sensation,  for  although   there   is 

1  That  is,  it  is  possible  to  effect  this  when  the  one  is  not  subaltern  to 
the  other,  as  it  may  be  shown  that  man  is  an  essence  if  we  take  biped  as 
a  medium,  or  walking,  or  disputing,  for  these  are  not  from  the  same  class 
as  the  former. 

2  That  is,  D  and  G,  media,  the  same  conclusion  A  B  is  proved. 
*  Cf.  Meiap.  lib.  v.  (vi.). 


CHAP.  XXXI.]         THE    POSTERIOR   AXALYT1CS.  309 

sensible  perception  of  such  a  thing  as  this,  ana  senses  is  not 
not  of  this  particular  thing,*  yet  it  is  necessary  *CNececert£e 
to  have  a  sensible  perception  of  this  particular   hujus  rei. 

.,.  ,  ,      r  i  i   -o     ,  ..  • •  •       Buhle. 

thing,  and  some  where  and  now.  Uut  it  is  impossi- 
ble sensibly  to  perceive  the  universal  and  in  all  things,  for  it  is 
not  this  particular  thing,  nor  now,  otherwise  it  would  not  be 
universal,  since  we  call  the  universal  that  which  is  always  and 
every  where.  Since  then  demonstrations  are  universal,  but 
these  cannot  be  perceived  by  sense,  it  is  plain  that  neither 
can  scientific  be  possessed  through  sense.  In  fact,  it  is  clear, 
that  even  if  we  could  perceive  by  sense  that  a  triangle  has 
angles  equal  to  two  right,  we  should  require  demonstration, 
and  not,  as  some  say,  know  this  scientifically,  for  it  is  necessary 
sensibly  to  perceive  the  singular,  but  science  is 
from  the  knowledge  of  the  universal.!  Where-  j+ibc^  *net]' 
fore  also  if  we  were  above  the  moon,  and  saw  the 
earth  opposite,  we  should  not  know  the  cause  of  an  eclipse 
(of  the  moon).  For  we  should  perceive  that  it  is  eclipsed, 
but  in  short  should  not  perceive  ichy,  since  there  would  not 
be  a  sensible  perception  of  the  universal.  Nevertheless,  from 
observing  this  frequently  to  happen,  by  investigation  of  the 
universal,  we  should  obtain  demonstration,  for  the  universal 
is  manifest  from  many  singulars,  but  is  valuable,  because  it 
discloses  the  cause,  wherefore  the  universal  (knowledge)  about 
such  things,  of  which  there  is  another  cause,  is  more  honour- 
able than  the  senses  and  apprehension  :  about  first  j  cf.  An.  Post, 
principles  however  there  is  another  reason. J2  »■  ch-  9- 

1  Aristotle  intends  to  show  that  sense  is  not  science ;  otherwise  since 
sense  apprehends  qualities,  as  sounds,  etc.,  it  may  seem  that  sense  and 
science  are  the  same;  but  the  fact  is,  that  though  they  are  employed 
about  the  same  things,  yet  they  are  not  so  after  the  same  manner,  for 
sense  apprehends  particularly,  but  science  universally.  Moreover  the 
perception  of  the  senses  is  limited  by  time  and  place,  but  science,  or  uni- 
versal  knowledge,  is  not  so  restricted,  so  that  the  ascertainment  of  the 
universal  is  beyond  the  scope  of  sensuous  perception.  Cf.  Physics;  De 
Animu,  lib.  ii.  and  iii. ;  Metap.  lib.  i.  ch.  1  ;  Magna  Moral,  lib.  i.  34,  and 
Moral.  Eud.  lib.  v.  c.  3. 

2  The  nearest  approach  to  simple  apprehension  is  t)  twv  atiaipirwi' 
voiiaiQ,  but  voi)oiq  is  variously  used,  and  in  its  widest  sense  will  embrace 
all  the  logical  operations.  Mansel.  See  also  Reid's  Works,  pp.  242,  692. 
Waitz  observes  upon  the  passage,  "  Quare  in  iis  quorum  causa  aliunde 
suspensa  est,  cognitio  quam  maxime  universalis  potior  est  omni  alia,  quae 
vel  ex  sensuum  affectione  gignatur  vel  ex  cognitione  sola  originem  ha- 
beat:   eorum  vero  quae  non  aliunde  probantur,  quippe  quibus  nitatur 


310  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

It  is  clearly  then  impossible  to  possess  scien- 
Lreha?egcer-  tific  knowledge  of  any  thing  demonstrable  by 
tain  things  un-  sensible  perception,  unless  some  one  should  affirm 
rtedeficfen^  that  sensible  perception  is  this,  to  possess  science 
of  sensible  per-  through  demonstration.    There  are  indeed  certain 

problems  which  are  referred  to  the  deficiency  of 
our  sensible  perception,1  for  some  if  we  should  see  them  we 
should  not  investigate,  not  as  knowing  from  seeing,  but  as 
possessing  the  universal  from  seeing.  For  instance,  if  we  saw 
glass  perforated,  and  the  light  passed  through  it,  it  would  be 

also  manifest  why  it  illuminates  in  consequence 
giaPss!Ce  °f  of  our  seeing  separately  in  each,*  and  at  the  same 
+  pieces.  time  perceiving  that  it  is  thus  with  all.f 

(Cf.  An.  Post.     Chap.  XXXIL— On  the  Difference  of  Principles  ac- 
i-  i.  10.)  cording  to  the  Diversity  of  Syllogisms. 

i.  Theimpos-  That  there  should  be  the  same  principles  of  all 
sibiiity  of  prin-  syllogisms  is  impossible,  first  (this  will  be  seen) 
syi'iogisms'be-  by  those  who  consider  logically.  For  some  syl- 
ing  identical,  logisms  are  true,  others  false,  since  it  is  possible 
to  conclude  the  true  from  the  false,  yet  this  but 
rarely  happens,  for  instance,  if  A  is  truly  predicated  of  C,  but 
the  middle  B  is  false,  for  neither  is  A  present  with  B  nor  B  with 
,   ,,  .    C.t     If  however  the  media  of  these  propositions 

I  Example    1.)  +  _       ,  „,    ,        „  ,       «,   ,     x      x 

are  assumed,  they  will  be  false,2  because  every 
false  conclusion  is  from  false  principles,  but  the  true  from 
true  principles,  and  the  false  and  the  true  are  different. 
Next,  neither  are  the  false  (deduced)  from  the  same  (princi- 
ples) with  themselves,  for  they  are  false  and  contrary  to  each 

omnis  ratiocinatio,  alia  ratio  est :  haec  enim  mente  ipsa  intuemur  et  quasi 
amplectimur. 

1  Philoponus  observes  that  Aristotle  added  this  observation  lest  any 
discrepancy  should  appear  to  exist  between  what  he  has  stated  here  and 
at  chapter  18.     Philop.  Schol. 

B  A 

Ex.  1 .  Every  stone  is  an  animal 
C  B 

Every  man  is  a  stone 
C  A 

• .  Every  man  is  an  animal. 
*  i.  e.  the  propositions  of  the  prosyllogisms,  if  the  former  are  to  be 
proved  by  the  latter. 


CHAP.  XXXII.]      THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  311 

other,  and  cannot  be  simultaneous,  for  instance,  it  is  impossible 
that  justice  should  be  injustice  or  timidity,  that  man  should 
be  a  horse  or  an  ox,  or  that  the  equal  should  be  greater  or  less. 
From  these  positions  indeed  (we  may  prove  it)   «  j  e  that 
thus,*  since  neither  are  there  the  same  principles   there  are  not 
of  all  the  true  (conclusions),  for  the  principles  of  CiPi|s  0feaunn 
many  are  different  in  genus,  and  are  not  suitable,   things- 
as  units  do  not  suit  points,  for  the  former  have  not  position, 
but  the  latter  have  it.      At  least  it  is  necessary  to   adapt 
(either)  to  media  or  from  above  or  below,  or  to  have  some 
terms   within    but  others  without.1  f      Nor  can    t  The  ex- 
there  possibly  be  certain  common  principles  from   jremes.  (Syi- 

m.  */  *■  i  loErismum  ) 

which  all  things  may  be  demonstrated :  I  mean  Buhie. 
by  common  as  to  affirm  or  to  deny  every  thing,  for  2- 
the  genera  of  beings  are  different,  and  some  are  present  with 
quantities,  but  others  with  qualities  alone,  with  which  there 
is  demonstration  through  the  common.  Again,  principles  are 
not  much  fewer  than  conclusions,  for  the  propositions  are 
principles,  but  the  propositions  subsist  when  a  term  is  either 
assumed  or  introduced.  Moreover,  conclusions  are  infinite, 
but  terms  finite ;  besides,  some  principles  are  from  necessity, 
but  others  contingent. 

To  those  therefore  who  thus  consider,  it  will  be   2.  Reply  to  ob- 
impossible  that  there  should  be  the  same  finite  Jjjj  mutakln 
principles  when  the  conclusions  are  infinite,  but   identity. 
if  any  one  should  reason  in  some  other  way,  for  instance, 
that  these  are  the  principles  of  geometry,  but  these 
of  reckoning,:}:  and  these  of  medicine,  what  is  this    1  \o-r,ouwv, 
statement  other  than  that  there  are  principles  of  J^tayfor9" 
the  sciences  ?  §  but  to  say  that  there  are  the  same   and  Buhie. 
principles  because  they  are  the  same  with  them-   principFe^oV" 
selves  is  ridiculous.il  for  thus  all  things  become   the  several  sci- 
the  same.      Still  neither  is  to  demonstrate  any    n  Because  no- 
thing from  all  things  to  investigate  whether  there   f^itedf™ 
are  the  same  principles  of  all,  since  this  would  be 

1  That  is,  if  principles  are  to  be  accommodated  to  another  science,  we 
must  so  arrange  the  terms  as  that  the  demonstrations  may  be  formed 
either  in  the  1st  figure,  wherein  the  middle  term  holds  the  middle  place; 
or  in  the  '2nd  figure,  where  it  occupies  the  hist  place,  and  is  above  both 
the  extremes ;  or  in  the  3rd  figure,  where  it  holds  the  last  place  under 
each  extreme.  Moreover,  some  must  be  formed  in  the  first,  but  otherg 
in  the  second  or  third  figure. 


312  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i 

*  i.  e.  Mathe-  very  silly.  For  neither  does  this  happen  in  evi- 
matk-s.  dent  disciplines,*  nor  is  it  possible  in  analysis,1 

since  immediate  propositions  are  principles,  and  another  con- 
.  go  that  he  elusion  arises,  when  an  immediate  proposition  is 
assumes  the  assumed. f  If  however  any  one  should  say  that  the 
many^onciu-  firs*  immediate  propositions  are  the  same  princi- 
sions-  pies,  there  is  one  in  each  genus,  but  it"  it  is  nei- 

ther possible  that  any  thing  can  be  demonstrated  as  it  ought 
to  be  from  all  (principles),  nor  that  they  should  be  so  different, 
as  that  there  should  be  different  ones  of  each  science,  it  re- 
mains that  the  principles  of  all  are  the  same  in 

sPecfes.iffer "     genus't  but  that  from  different  principles  differ- 
ent sciences  (are  demonstrated).      Now  this   is 
§  ch.  7.  evidently  impossible,  for  it  has  been  shown  S  that 

3    Principles  .  ^ 

(c,px.ai)  two-  the  principles  are  different  in  genus  of  those 
fold,  i£ <Sv  and  things  which  are  generically  different,  for  princi- 
ples are  two-fold,  viz.  from  which  and  about  which, 
those  indeed  from  which  are  common,2  but  those  about  uhich 
are  peculiar,  for  instance,  number  and  magnitude. 


Vid.  Ethics,     Chap.  XXXIII. —  Upon  the  Difference  beticeen  Science 
vi.ch.  3,  a."* 
b.  iii.  ch.  2. 


b'vi-ch-3'and  and  Opinio^.  || 


l.  science  is  The  object  of  scientific  knowledge  and  science 
rublfs^  '  ai  (itself)  differs  from  the  object  of  opinion,  and  from 
through  things    opinion,  because  science  is  universal,  and  subsists 

necessary:  m-        • f  '  .  ' 

teiiecttheprin-  through  things  necessary,  and  what  is  necessary 
cipie  of  science.  cannot  subsist  otherwise  than  it  does  :  some 
things  however  are  true,  and  subsist,  yet  may  possibly  subsist 
otherwise.  It  is  evident  then  that  science  is  not  conversant 
with  these,  (for  else  things  which  are  capable  of  subsisting  other- 
wise, could  not  possibly  subsist  otherwise).      Yet 

IT  See  Ethics,  b.  .,/       ...    „    r.K         J  ..  ,     ,'      T       .. 

vi  ch.  2  and  3,  neither  is  intellect!  conversant  with  such,  (for  I  call 
Bohn"s'editteS'  inte^ect  tne  principle  of  science,3)  nor  indemon- 
*  vnox^is.       strable  science,  and  this  is  the  notion  *  of  an  imme- 

1  If  any  one  were  to  analyze  the  different  sciences  into  their  principles, 
he  would  not  be  able  to  analyze  them  into  the  same,  but  into  different 
principles. 

2  As  axioms,  see  ch.  10;  also  table  of  the  principles  of  science.  Cf. 
Sanderson's  Logic,  b.  iii.  ch.  11  ;  Mill's  Logic,  vol.  i.  p.  197;  Metap.  v. 
and  vi. 

3  Because  of  our  cognizance  of  axioms  by  it 


CHAP.  XXXIII.]      THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  313 

diate  proposition.     But  intellect,  science,  and  opi-    See  Mansel's 
nion,  and  what  is  asserted  through  these,  are  true,    n°t^c'  p' 5' 
wherefore  it  remains  that  opinion   is  conversant 
with  the  true  or  false,  which  yet  may  have  a  various  subsist- 
ence, but  this  is  the  notion  of  an  immediate  and  not  neces- 
sary proposition.       This   also  agrees  with  what  .  . 

J    r    K.     ,    .,       .   .       .  .  , ,  :    .,  2.  opinion  con- 

appears,  lor  both  opinion  is  unstable,  and  its  na-    versant  with 

ture  is  of  this  kind,1  besides,  no  one  thinks  that  thenon-neces- 
he  opines,  but  that  he  knows,  when  he  thinks  it 
impossible  for  a  thing  to  subsist  otherwise  than  it  does,  but 
when  he  thinks  that  it  is  indeed  thus,  yet  that  nothing  hinders* 
it  being  otherwise,  then  he  thinks  that  he  opines  ;  *  so  waitz, 
opinion  as  it  were  being  conversant  with  a  thing  and'Huhie^1"1 
of  this  kind,  but  science  with  what  is  necessary.     KuXuei. 

How  then  is  it  possible  f  to  opine  and  know    +  Taylor  and 
the  same  thing',  and  why  will  opinion  not  be  sci-    B_ulllf  inser! 

b'  m  J  r  _  _  on — "  non  li- 

ence,  if  a  person  admits  that  every  thing  which  cet,"  "it  is  not 
he  knows  he  may  opine  ?  for  both  he  who  knows  waitzandBek- 
and  he  who  opines  will  follow  through  media  till   keromitit. 

,  ...  , .  ,         •  n  .1       n  3-  Solution  of 

they  come  to  things  immediate,  so  that  if  the  former  an  inquirywhy 

knows,   he  also  who  opines   knows.      For  as  it  oBiifio'n^a.8*68 

is  possible  to  opine  that  a  thing  is,  so  likewise  not  be  science. 

why  it  is,  and  this  is  the  medium.      Or  \  if  he  so  "shaiFwesay." 

conceives  things  which  cannot  subsist  otherwise,  Taylor,   waitz 

.„.        iii         if..-  i  i  i-i        ,         omits,  but  Bek- 

as  it  he  had  the  definitions  through  which  the  ker  retains  the 
demonstrations  are  framed,  he  will  not  opine,  but  iuestlon- 
know ;  but  if  that  they  are  true,  yet  that  these  are  not  pre- 
sent with  them  essentially,  and  according  to  form,  he  will 
opine  and  not  know  truly  both  the  that  and  the  why,  if  in- 
deed he  should  opine  through  things  immediate  ;  but  if  not 

1  In  fact,  as  Aldrich  observes,  "  ei  (opinioni)  nulla  competit  certitudo 
sed  in  ipsa  sui  ratiune  includit  ibrmidinem  oppositi :  sunt  opinioni  tamen 
gradus  quidam  ad  certitudincin."  For  the  most  admirable  example  of 
all  the  vacillation  of  opinion  from  surmise  to  certainty,  and  of  the  desire 
for  that  full  knowledge  and  assurance  which  after  all  will  crush  the  heart, 
"  the  doom  it  dreads,  yet  dwells  upon,"  see  Shakspeare's  Othello, 
passim,  but  especially  act  iii.  scene  3 : 

"  Oth.  By  the  world, 
I  think  my  wife  be  honest ;  and  think  she  is  not ; 
I  think  that  thou  art  just ;  and  think  thou  art  not; 
I'll  have  some  proof." 

See  also  Butler's  Analogy,  Introduction  on  Probable  Evidence.  Cf.  Top. 
i.  1 ;   Aldrich,  Whately,  Sanderson's  and  Hill's  Logic,  in  verb. 


314  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  i. 

through  the  immediate,  he  will  only  opine  that  they  are. 
Still  opinion  and  science  are  not  altogether  conversant  with 
the  same  thing,  but  as  both  the  true  and  the  false  opinion  are 
in  a  manner  about  the  same  thing,  thus  also  science  and 
opinion  are  conversant  with  the  same.1  For  as  some  say  that 
true  and  false  opinion  are  of  the  same ;  absurd  consequences 

follow  both  in  other  respects,  and  also  that  he 
iH.ch.^etb'      who  opines  falsely  does  not  opine.2  *     Now  since 

the  same  thing  is  stated  in  several  ways,  in  one 
way  there  may  be,  and  in  another  there  cannot  be  (a  true 
and  false  opinion  of  the  same).  For  to  opine  truly  that  the 
diameter  of  a  square  is  commensurate  with  its  side,  is  ab- 
surd, but  because  the  diameter  about  which  there  are  (con- 
trary) opinions  is  the  same  thing,  thus  also  they  are  of  the 
same  thing,  but  the  essence  of  each  according  to  the  definition 
is  not  the  same.3  In  like  manner  also  knowledge  and  opinion 
are  conversant  with  the  same  thing,  for  the  former  is  so  con- 
versant with  animal  as  that  it  is  impossible  animal  should  not 
exist,  but  the  latter  so  as  that  it  may  possibly  not  exist,  as  if 
the  one  should  be  conversant  with  that  which  is  man  essen- 
tially, but  the  other  with  man  indeed,  yet  not  with  what  is 
t  But  accident-  man  essentially  ;f  for  it  is  the  same  thing,  that  is, 
ally'  man,  but  not  the  same  as  to  the  manner. 

4.  We  cannot,  From  these  then  it  is  clearly  impossible  to  opine 
at  one  and  the    an(j  know  the  same  thing  at  the  same  time,  for 

same  time,  .  °  ' 

know,  and  otherwise  at  one  and  the  same  time  a  man  might 
opme"  have  a  notion  that  the  same  thing  could  and  could 

not  subsist  otherwise,  which  is  impossible.  In  different  (men) 
indeed  each  (of  these)  may  be  possible  about  the  same  thing, 

1  Science  is  however  distinguished  from  opinion,  by  the  certainty  of  its 
subject :  error  also  consists  with  certainty  of  the  subject,  but  opinion 
cannot  consist  with  it.  Vide  Mansel's  note,  p.  102  ;  Sanderson's  defini- 
tions. Cf.  also  Anal.  Post.  i.  6.  The  whole  subject  is  well  discussed  by 
Hill  (Logic,  p.  275,  et  seq.),  and  upon  the  distinction  of  the  dialectic 
and  demonstrative  syllogism,  as  enuuciative  of  opinion  and  science,  the 
reader  will  find  some  valuable  remarks  in  Mansel,  and  Crakanthorpe's 
Logic.    Cf.  Top.  i.  1. 

2  He  here  glances  at  the  opinion  entertained  by  Protagoras  and  the 
sophists,  who  asserted  that  truth  and  falsehood  were  only  in  opinion,  and 
that  if  every  opinion  is  true,  false  opinion  is  not  opinion. 

3  From  the  thing  being  considered  in  two  ways,  there  are  two  essences 
of  the  thing,  and  the  diameter  is  assumed  in  true  opinion  in  one  way,  and 
in  false  opinion  in  another.     Taylor. 


CHAP.  XXXIV.]     THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  315 

as  we  have  said,*  but  in  the  same  (man)  it  is  im-   ,  vide  Aidrich 
possible  even  thus,  since  he  would  have  a  notion   in-verb.  ••  opi- 
at  the  same  time,  for  instance,  that  man  is  essen- 
tially animal,  (for  this  it  is  to  be  impossible  not  to  be  an 
animal,)  and  is  not  essentially  an  animal,  for  this  it  is  to  be 
possible  not  to  be  an  animal. 

For  the  rest,  how  it  is  necessary  to  distinguish  between  dis- 
course and  intellect,  and  science  and  art,  and  prudence  and 
wisdom,  belongs  rather  partly  to  the  physical,  and  partly  to 
the  ethical  theory.1 

Chap.  XXXIV.— Of  Sagacity. +  t  Cf.  Ethics, 

J         J        *   '  b.  vi.  ch.  9 

Sagacity  is  a  certain  happy  extempore  conjee-  j  Definition 

ture  of  the  middle  term,  as  if  a  man  perceiving  of  sagacity. 

that  the  moon  always  has  that  part  lustrous  which  ££££&  x'pola 

is  towards  the  sun,  should  straightway  understand  To;;  uiao" :  in" 

StiillCtS 

why  this  occurs,  viz.  because  it  is  illuminated  by 

the  sun,  or  seeing  a  man  talking  to  a  rich  person,  should  know 

that  it  is  in  order  to  borrow  money  of  him,  or  that  persons 

are  friends,  because  they  are  enemies  of  the  same 

man  ;  for  he  who  perceives  the  extremes^  knows   \^\  eonclu" 

all  the  middle  causes.     Let  to  be  lustrous  in  the 

part  toward  the  sun  be  A,  to  be  illuminated  by  the  sun  B, 

the  moon  C.     Wherefore  B  to  be  illuminated  by  the  sun  is 

present  with  the  moon  C,  but  A  to  be  lustrous  in  the  part 

turned  towards  that   by  which  it  is  illuminated  is  present 

with  B,  hence  also  A  is  present  with  C  through 

t.   r  r  °        §  Example  ,1.) 

1  Cf.  Biese,  vol.  i.  p.  89,  327 ;  Hamilton's  Reid,  p.  768.  Atdvoia.  is 
the  progress  of  the  intuitive  intellect  (vovg)  in  investigating  truth,  and  is 
perhaps  best  rendered  here  "  discourse,"  though  the  latter  applies  both  to 
it  and  to  Xoyicr/ioc.  Upon  these  terms,  cf.  Mansel's  note,  pp.  4 — 6,  and 
upon  the  powers  or  energies  themselves,  see  Ethics,  b.  vi.,  Bonn's  edition, 
and  De  Anima. 

B  A 

Ex.  1.  Whatever  is  illuminated  by  the  sun  shines  in  the  part  towards 
the  sun 

C  B 

The  moon  is  illuminated  by  the  sun 
C  A 

• .  Tie  moon  shines  in  the  part  towards  the  sun. 


316 


Aristotle's  org  anon. 


book  n. 


BOOK  II. 


Chap.  I. — That  the  subjects  of  Scientific  Investigation  are  four. 


I.  Subjects  of 
investigation  : 
the  that ;  the 
why;  the  if; 
and  the  what. 
A  thing  is  to 

OTf  TO,  OiOTi,  el 
ZoTIV,  T*  €<TTtv. 

Instances. 


The  subjects  of  investigation  are  equal  in  num- 
ber to  the  things  which  we  scientifically  know ; 
but  we  investigate  four  things  ;  that  a  thing  is, 
why  it  is,  if  it  is,  ivhat  it  is.  For  when  we  in- 
quire whether  it  is  this,  or  that,  having  reference 
to  a  number  (as  whether  the  sun  is  eclipsed  or  not) 
we  investigate  the  that,  and  a  sign  of  this  is  that 
when  we  have  found  that  it  is  eclipsed  we  desist  from  our  in- 
quiries, and  if  we  knew  from  the  first  that  it  is  eclipsed,  we 
do  not  inquire  whether  it  is  so.  But  when  we  know  the 
that,  we  investigate  the  why,  for  instance,  when  we  know  that 
directing  there  is  an  eclipse,  and  there  is  an  earthquake, 
we  inquire  why  there  is  an  eclipse,  and  an  earth- 
quake. These  things  indeed  we  investigate  thus,* 
but  some  after  another  manner, f  for  instance,  if 
there  is,  or  is  not,  a  centaur  or  a  God.  I  say  if 
there  is  or  is  not,  simply,1  and  not  if  it  is  white 
When  however  we  know  that  a  thins- 


our  attention 
tomanythings. 
t  Simply  con- 
sidering one 
thing. 

X  Bekker  and 
Waitz  end 
here  :  Taylor 

and  Buhle  add    or   not. 
the  opening 

sentence  of  the   is,  we  inquire  what  it  is,  tor  instance,  what  God, 
next  chapter.     0r  what  man  is.  J 


Chap.  II. —  That  all  Investigation  has  reference  to  the  Discovery  of 

the  Middle  Term. 

I.  The  former  The  things  then  which  we  investigate,  and  which 
Hom "mayl be  having  discovered  we  know,  are  such  and  so 
reduced  to  two,   many,  but  when  we  inquire  the  that  or  if  a  thing 

'  Vide  Trendelen.  Elem.  Log.  p.  74.  By  simply,  he  means  an  inves- 
tigation into  the  mere  existence  of  the  thing,  but  when  an  inquiry  as  to  the 
™  on  is  made,  then  it  becomes  a  question  of  the  quality.  Upon  the  ar- 
gument of  this  whole  book,  see  Kuhn's  work,  Hal.  1844  ;  we  may  remark 
that  the  question  or  to  lyrov^vov  here,  has  a  more  extensive  application 
than  what  Aldrich  assigns  to  it,  since  two  of  the  questiones  scibiles,  "  an 
sit,"  and  "quid  self,"  cannot  in  all  cases  be  determined  syllogistically. 
Cf.  ch.  3,  of  this  book.     See  aiso  Mansel's  Appendix,  note  B. 


CHAP.  II. J  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  317 

is  simply,  then  we  inquire  whether  there  is  a  concerning  the 
medium  of  it  or  not,  but  when  knowing,  either  ^ere^te'oiie1 
that  it  is,  or  if  it  is,  either  in  part  or  simply,1  we  and  what  it  is. 
again  investigate  why  it  is,  or  what  it  is,  then  we  inquire 
what  the  middle  is.  But  I  mean  by  the  that  if  it  is  in  a 
part  and  simply,  in  a  part  indeed  (as)  is  the  moon  eclipsed  or 
increased  ?  for  in  such  things  we  inquire  if  a  thing  is  or  is 
not  ;  but  simply  (as)  if  there  is  a  moon  or  not,  or  if  night  is 
or  net.*  In  all  these  inquiries  it  occurs  that  we  *  a  question  of 
investigate  either  if  there  is  a  middle  or  what  the  the  whole,  not 
middle  is,  for  the  cause  is  the  middle,  and  this  is  2,  The  middle 
investigated  in    all    things.     Is    there    then    an    1S  that  wh'th 

O   .  .0  ......         expresses   the 

eclipse  r  is  there  a  certain  cause  or  not  r  atter  this,  cause  why  the 
when  we  know  that  there  is,  we  inquire  what  "ated'of  the"11" 
this  is.  Fur  the  cause  of  a  thing  not  being  this  or  minor. 
that,  but  simply  substance,  or  not  simply,  but  something  of 
those  which  subsist  per  se,  or  accidentally,  is  the  middle.  I 
mean  by  what  is  simply  (substance)  the  subject,  as  the  moon,  or 
the  earth,  or  the  sun,  or  a  triangle,  but  by  a  certain  thing,  (as) 
an  eclipse,  equality,  inequality  f  if  it  is  in  the 
middle  or  not.|  For  in  all  these  it  is  evident  that  Jhfangksl/a 
what  a  thing  is  and  toll)/  it  is  are  the  same ;  what  triangle. 

v  «j  •       .•  »  v    1  ,    j  4l  X  Refeiring  to 

is  an  eclipse  r  a  privation  ot  light  tram  the  moon   the  earth,  as  in 
through  the  interposition  of  the  earth.      Why  is   the  centre  of 

=  r  ...  i-         j  a    the  spheres. 

there  an  eclipse,  or  why  is  the  moon  eclipsed  r 
because  its  light  fails  through  the  interposition  of  the  earth.2 
What  is  symphony?  a  ratio  of  numbers  in  sharp  and  flat. 
Why  does  the  sharp  accord  with  the  flat  ?  because  the  sharp 
and  flat  have  the  ratio  of  numbers.  Do  then  the  sharp  and 
flat  accord?- is  there  then  a  ratio  of  them  in  numbers?  as- 
suming that  there  is,  what  then  is  the  ratio  ? 

That  the  inquiry  is  of  the  middle  those  things 
prove  whose  middle  falls  within  the  cognizance  of  fnv^tigtt'e  the 
the  senses,  since  we  inquire  when  we  have  not  a   middle,  if  the 
sensible  perception,  as  of  an  eclipse,  whether  it  is   and  its1  cause, 

or  not.     But  if  we  were  above  the  moon  we  should   fl"  within  the 
.  ,         .  n  ,        .         .  ,  ,    ,        cognizance  ot 

not  inquire  neither  it,  nor  why,  but  it  would  be   our  senses. 
immediately  evident,  as  from  sensible  perception   {^t^o'asn 
we  should  also  obtain  knowledge  of  the  universal ; 

1   In  part  that  it  is,  or  simply  if  it  is. 

-  Upon   the  reduction   ol   this  demonstration  to  syllogistic  form,  see 
Aquinas  Opusc.  3s,  and  Crakanthorpe  Loir.  lib.  iv.  cap.   1. 


S18  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  11. 

for  sense  (vould  show  us)  that  the  earth  is  now  opposed, 
for  it   would  be  evident  that  there  is  now  an 
fibC£  Metap'      eclipse,  and  from  this  there  would  arise  the  uni- 
versal. '  * 
As  therefore  we  say,  the  knowledge  of  the  Awhat  is  the  same 
as  the  knowledge  of  the  why,  and,vthis  is  either1  simply,  and  not 
somewhat  of  things  inherent,  ^of  it  is  of  things  inherent,  as 
that  there  are  two  right  angles  or  that  it  is  greater  or  less. 


Chap.  III. —  Upon  the  Difference  between  Demonstration  and 

Definition. 

That  all  investigations  then  are  an  inquiry  of  the  middle  is 
evident,  but  let  us  show  how  tohat  a  thing  is,  is  demon- 
strated, and  what  is  the  method  of  training  up  a  thing  to  its 
,.  ,  .  i,  principles,2!  also  what  a  definition  is,  and  of  what 
e.  avahiaew  subjects  doubting  first  about  these.  But  let  the 
commencement  of  the  future  (doubts)  be  that 
which  is  most  appropriate  to  the  following  discussion,  since 
,   w  perhaps  a  man  might  doubt  whether  it  is  possible 

1.  We  cannot       r     ,     r  °      ,  .  ,  ,.r 

know  by  defi-  to  know  the  same  thing,  and  according  to  the 
subjecfcapabie  same  D7  definition  and  demonstration,  or  whether 
of demonstra-  it  is  impossible?  For  definition  seems  to  be  of 
what  a  thing  is,  but  every  thing  (which  signifies) 
what  a  thing  is,  is  universal  and  affirmative,  but  some  syllo- 
gisms are  negative,  others  not  universal ;  for  instance,  all  those 
in  the  second  figure  are  negative,  but  those  in  the  third  not 
universal.  Next,  neither  is  there  definition  of  all  affirmatives 
in  the  first  figure,  as  that  every  triangle  has  angles  equal  to 
two  right  angles ;   the  reason  of  this  is,  because  to  know 

1  By  sensible  perception  that  of  the  universal  is  produced. 

-  That  is,  how  definition  is  reduced  to  demonstration,  for  every  de- 
finition is  either  the  principle  or  the  conclusion  of  demonstration,  or  it 
alone  differs  from  demonstration  in  the  position  of  terms,  as  was  shown 
in  ch.  8,  of  the  preceding  book.  Taylor.  Upon  the  subject  of  this 
chapter,  and  the  subsequent  ones,  the  reader  is  referred  to  the  truly 
valuable  remarks  in  Mansel's  Appendix,  note  B.,  which  want  of  room 
prevents  my  fully  quoting,  and  justice  to  the  excellent  treatment  the 
author  has  shown  of  his  subject,  forbids  me  to  abridge.  In  many  cases 
I  have  been  compelled  to  give  only  references,  where  otherwise  I  would 
have  entered  into  greater  detail.  The  student  will  do  well  also  to  con- 
sult Rassow,  Aristot.  de  notionis  def.  doctr.,  and  Crakanthorpe's  Logic. 
Cf.  also  Top.  i.  5  and  6,  4  and  14;   Metap.  vi.  11 ;  De  Anima,  i.  1. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  319 

scientifically  that  which  is  demonstrable,  is  to  possess  de- 
monstration, so  that  if  there  is  demonstration  in  regard  to 
things  of  this  kind,  there  can  evidently  not  be  also  definition 
of  them,  for  a  person  might  know  by  definition  without  de- 
monstration, since  nothing  prevents  the  possession  of  it  at  one 
and  the  same  time.  A  sufficient  evidence  of  this  is  also 
derived  from  induction,  for  we  have  never  known  by  de- 
finition, any  of  those  which  are  inherent  per  se  nor  which  are 
accidents  ;  besides,  if  definition  be  a  certain  indication  of  sub- 
stance, it  is  evident  that  such  things  are  not  substances. 

Clearly  then,  there  is  not   definition  of  every 
thing   of  which  there  is  also  demonstration,  but   nionsTrationaii 
what,  is  there  then  demonstration  of  every  thing   those  which  are 
of  which  there  is  definition  or  not  ?  there  is  one   fmition. 
reason   and  the  same  also  of  this.*     For  of  one   *bo>™posed 
thing,  so  far  as  it  is  one,  there  is  one  science,  so 
that  if  to  know  that   which    is   demonstrable   be   to  possess 
demonstration,    an  impossibility  would  happen,  for   he   who 
possesses   definition   would   know    scientifically   without    de- 
monstration.    Besides,    the   principles  of  demonstration   are 
definitions,  of  which  it  has  been  shown  before,  there  will  not 
be  demonstrations,-!"  since  either  principles  will  be 
demonstrable,  and  principles  of  principles,  and  this    ch^and1^1 
would  proceed  to  infinity,  or  the  first  (principles) 
will  be  indemonstrable  definitions. 

Yet  if  there  are  not  of  every  thing  and  the   3.  in  fact,  no- 
same,  may  there  not  be  definition  and  demonstra-    thing  capable 

..      J  ...  .     .  „  ...  of  definition 

tion  of  a  certain  thing  and  the  same  r  or  is  it  1m-  admits  de- 
possible  ?  since  there  is  not  demonstration  of  what  monstratlon- 
there  is  definition.  For  definition  is  of  what  a  thing  is, 
and  of  substance,  but  all  demonstrations  appear  to  suppose 
and  assume  what  a  thing  is,  as  mathematics,  what  is  unity 
and  what  an  odd  number,  and  the  rest  in  like  manner.  More- 
over every  demonstration  shows  something  of  somewhat,  as 
that  it  is,  or  that  it  is  not,  but  in  definition  one  thing  is  not 
predicated  of  another,  as  neither  animal  of  biped,  4.  one  part  of  a 
nor  this  of  animal,  nor  figure  of  superficies,  for  su-    definition  is 

/»••./>  c  c    •  a  not  predicated 

perficies  is  not  figure,  nor  figure  superficies.  Again,    0f  another. 
it  is  one  thins  to  show  what  a  thins  is,  but  an-   yweHill'a 

0  °  Lopic,  and 

other  to  show  that  it  is,  definition  then  shows  what    Whately  on 
a  thing  is,  but  demonstration  that  this  thing,  either    "  Definitlon-" 


320  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  n. 

is  or  is  not  of  this.  Of  a  different  thing  indeed  there  is  a  dif- 
ferent demonstration,  unless  it  should  be  as  a  certain  part  of  the 
whole.  I  say  this  because  the  isosceles  has  been  shown  (to  have 
angles  equal)  to  two  right,  if  every  triangle  has  been  shown  (to 
»  The  isosceles  ^ave  them),  f°r  that  is  a  Part,  but  this  a  whole :  * 
being  a  species  these  however,  that  a  thing  is,  and  what  it  is,  do 
to  it^a'part   not  thus  subsist  in  reference  to  each  other,  since 

to  a  whole.  the  one  js  not  a  par^  0f  tJje  other. 

Evidently  then  there  is  neither  entirely  demon- 
tion.eCapitUla"    stration  of  what  there  is  definition,  nor  entirely  de- 
finition of  what  there  is  demonstration  ;  hence  in 
t  Definition       short  it  is  impossible  to  have  both  f  of  the  same 
*£itionTn"       tmng?  so  that  it  is  also  evident  that  definition  and 

♦  -m.    ,.-  demonstration  will  neither  be  the  same,  nor  the 

%  The  things  .        ,    .        ,  ,  ,  .  '     . 

defined  and  de-   one  contained  in  the  other,  otherwise  their  sub- 

monstrated.         jectgi  woul(j  subsist  similarly.| 

Chap.  IV. —  That  the  Definition  of  a  thing  cannot  be  demonstrated. 

1.  in  order  to  ^jET  then  so  far  these  things  be  matters  of  doubt, 

collect  by  a  syi-  but  as  to  what  a  thing  is  whether  is  there,  or  is 

thing  is,  the  there  not,  a  syllogism  and  a  demonstration  of  it,  as 

midu!lterm  the  present  discussion  supposed  ?  for  a  syllogism 

ought  to  ex-  r  ...  n  ,  i  , 

press  the  defi-  shows  something  in  respect  oi  somewhat  through 
mtIon-  a  medium,  but  the  (definition)  what  a  thing  is, 

is  both  peculiar  and  is  predicated  in  respect  of  what  it  is. 
Th  nat  Now  it  is  necessary  that  these  should  reciprocate  :  |i 
of  the  thing  for  if  A  is  the  property  of  C,  it  is  evidently  alsc 
wWchttis  the  that  of  B,  and  that  of  C,  so  that  all  §  reciprocate 
nature.  with  each  other.     Nevertheless,  if  A  is  present 

with  every  B  in  respect  of  what  it  is,  and  uni- 
versally B  is  predicated  of  every  C  in  respect  of  what  it  is,  it 
is  also  necessary  that  A  should  be  predicated  of  C  in  the  ques- 
tion what  it  is.  Still  if  some  one  should  assume  without  this 
reduplication,2  it  will  not  be  necessary  that  A  should  be  predi- 
cated of  C  in  the  question  what  a  thing  is,  though  A  should 
f  in  the  major,   ^e  predicated  of  B^[  in  the  same  question,  but  not 

*  intneminor.   of  those  of  which  B  is  predicated  in  this  question.* 

Now  both  these |  will  signify  what  a  thing  (C)  is, 

'  to.  inro  Kti/Atva,  h.  e.  finis  ad  quem  tendit  utraque  vel  id  quod  utraqua 
conricere  vult.     Waitz. 

2  That  is,  simply  saying  that  A  is  attributed  to  B,  and  B  tc  C. 


CHAP.  IV. "1  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  321 

wherefore  B  will  also  be  the  definition  of  C,  hence  if  both 
signify  what  a  thing  is,  and  what  the  very  nature  of  it  is, 
there  will  be  the  very  nature  of  a  thing  prior  in  the  middle 
term.  Universally  also,  if  it  is  possible  to  show  what  man 
is,  let  C  be  man,  but  A  what  he  is,  whether  biped  animal, 
or  any  thing  else ;  in  order  then  that  a  conclusion  should  be 
drawn,  A  must  necessarily  be  predicated  of  every  B,  and  of 
this  there  will  be  another  middle  definition,  so  that  this  also 
will  be  a  definition  of  a  man,  wherefore  a  person  assumes 
what  he  ought  to  show,  for  B  also  is  the  definition  of 
a  man. 

We  must  however  consider  it  in  two  proposi-   2.  a  twofold 
tions,  and  in  first  and  immediate  (principles),  for   consideration, 
what  is  stated  becomes  thus  especially  evident :  they  there- 
fore who  show  what  the  soul  is,  or  what  man  or  any  thing 
else  is,  by  conversion,  beg  the  question,1  as  if  a  man  should 
assume  the  soul  to  be  that  which  is  the  cause  to  itself  of 
life,*  and  that  this  is  number  moving  itself,f  he 
must  necessarily  so  assume  as  a  postulate  that  the   t  The  major, 
soul  is   number  moving  itself,  as  that  it  is  the   pf-.de ; Anim- 

b.  i  cfii  4    16. 

same  thing.  For  it  does  not  follow  if  A  is  con- 
sequent to  B,  and  this  to  C,  that  A  will  therefore  be  the 
definition  of  the  essence  of  C,  but  it  will  be  only  possible  to 
say  that  this  is  true,  nor  if  A  is  that  which  is  predicated 
essentially  of  every  B.  For  the  very  nature  of  animal  is 
predicated  of  the  very  nature  of  man,  since  it  is  true  that 
whatever  exists  as  man,  exists  as  animal,  (just  as  every  man 
is  animal,)  yet  not  so,  as  for  both  to  be  one  thing.|  t  Because  one 
If  then  a  person  does  not  assume  this,  he  will  not   is  genus,  the 

1  In  the  minor  in  fact  the  terms  so  reciprocate  as  to  become  identical, 
and  the  very  nature  of  a  thing,  and  that  of  which  it  is  the  very  nature,  are 
the  same.  The  whole  argument  goes  to  show  that  no  definition,  as  such, 
can  be  proved,  but  the  endeavour  necessarily  results  in  a  petitio  principii. 
and  the  reason  is  simply  because  a  definition  can  be  predicated  essentia1  ly 
( f  v  rip  ti  tan )  of  nothing  but  that,  of  which  it  is  the  definition  ;  and  sin., 
to  prove  a  conclusion  concerning  the  essence,  the  premises  must  be  of  th* 
same  character,  the  assumed  middle  must  be  identical  with  the  minor, 
and  the  major  premise  with  the  conclusion.  The  argument  is  used 
against  Xenocrates.  Cf.  Scholia,  p.  242,  b.  35.  Trendelenburg,  de  An.  p. 
'273.  Kuhn,  de  Notionis  Definitione,  p.  11.  Mansers  Logic,  Appendix 
B.  In  some  passages  (Metap.  vi.  5,  b  ;  vi.  4,  12)  Aristotle  declares  sub- 
stances alone  capable  of  definition,  but  in  a  wider  sense,  as  used  throughout 
the  Post.  Anal.,  the  remark  is  applicable  both  to  substances  and  attributes 

Y 


322 


ARISTOTLE  S    OKGANON. 


1  BOOK  II. 


other  species. 
3.  He  who 
proves  the  de- 
finition by  a 
syllogism  begs 
tiie  question. 

tio  principii. 


conclude  that  A  is  the  very  nature  and  sub- 
stance of  C,  but  if  he  thus  assume  it,  he  will 
assume  prior  to  the  conclusion  that  B  is  the  de- 
finition of  the  essence  of  C.  Therefore  there  has 
been  no  demonstration,  for  he  has  made  a  "  peti- 


Chap.  V. — That  there  is  no  Conclusion  by  Divisions  proved. 


1.  That  the 
method  by  di- 
vision is  in- 
conclusive. 
*  An.  Prior,  i. 
31. 

t  The  members 
of  division. 
%  The  defini- 
tion to  be 
proved. 

§  The  admitted 
premises. 


Nevertheless,  neither  does  the  method  througt 
divisions  infer  a  conclusion,  as  we  observed  in  the 
analysis  about  figures,*  since  it  is  never  necessary 
that  when  these  things  exist,  f  that  J  should  exist, 
as  neither  does  he  demonstrate  who  forms  an  in- 
duction. For  the  conclusion  ought  not  to  inquire 
nor  to  exist  from  being  granted,  but  it  necessarily 
is,  when  they§  exist,  although  the  respondent 
does  not  acknowledge  it.  Is  man  (for  instance) 
animal  or  inanimate,1  if  he  has  assumed  him  to  be  an  animal, 
it  has  net  been  syllogistically  concluded.  Again,  every  ani- 
mal is  either  pedestrian  or  aquatic,  he  assumes  it  pedestrian, 
and  that  man  is  that  whole  animal  pedestrian,  is  not  neces- 
sary from  what  is  said,  but  he  assumes  also  this.  It  signifies 
nothing  however,  whether  he  does  this  in  respect  of  many 
2.  The  same  things  or  few,  since  it  is  the  same  thing  ;  to  those 
reasoning  good  therefore  who  thus  proceed,  and  in  what  is  capa- 
definUion.8  °  ble  of  syllogistic  conclusion,  this  use  is  unsyllo- 
gistic.  For  what  prevents  the  whole  of  this|| 
being  true  of  man,  yet  without  enunciating  what 
a  thing  is,  or  the  very  nature  of  it  ?  Again,  what  prevents 
something  being  added  to,  or  taken  away  from,  or  exceeding 
the  essence  ?  2 

Negligence  then  happens  about  these  things, 
but  we  may  avoid  it  by  assuming  all  things  (as 
granted)  in  respect  of  what  a  thing  is,  and  the 
first  being  made  a  postulate  by  arranging  the  order 


Pedestrian. 


3.  A  rule  ap- 
plied for  divi- 
sional defini- 
tion. 


1  This  is  an  interrogation  of  one,  investigating  a  definition  by  division. 

2  That  is,  that  something  may  be  superfluous  or  defective  in  the  defini- 
tion. Cf.  rules  for  definition  in  the  common  Logics ;  also  Passow,  Arist 
de  Notionis  Defin.  Doct.,  Crakanthorpe,  and  Sanderson,  and  especially 
Boethius  de  Divisione. 


CHAP.   VI. J  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  323 

in  division,  omitting  nothing.   This  however  is  requisite,  for  it 
is  necessary  that  there  should  be  an  individual,    .   „ 

?    ,  ,  .  ...  '     4.   By  constant 

yet  nevertheless  there  is  not  a  syllogism,  but  if  so   division,  when 
it  indicates  after  another  manner.   And  this  is  not   nitfonTs'^*" 
at  all  absurd,  since  neither  perhaps  does  he  who   rived  ?l-  we 
makes  an  induction  demonstrate,  though  at  the   rhVat  the  fn- 
same  time  he  renders  something  manifest,  but  he   dlvidual- 
who  selects  definition  from  division  does  not  state  a  syllo- 
gism.1    For  as  in  conclusions  without  media,  if  a  man  state 
that  from  such  things  being  granted,  this  particular  thing 
necessarily  exists,  it  is  possible  to  inquire  why,  thus  also  is  it 
in  definitions  by  division.      What  is  man  ?    A  mortal  animal, 
pedestrian,  biped,  without  wings.    Why  ?  according  to  each 
addition,'2  for  he  will  state  and  show  by  division  as  he  thinks 
that  every  one   is  either  mortal  or  immortal.      The  whole 
however  of  such  a  sentence  is  not  definition,*   *  For  the  defi- 
wherefore  though  it  should  be  demonstrated  by   nifion  h!iS  t0  be 
division,   yet  the  definition  does  not  become   a   it,  i.e.  a  mortal 

Syllogism.3  animal. 

Chap.  VI. —  Case  of  one  Proposition  defining  the  Definition  itself. 

Is  it  however  possible  to  demonstrate  what  a   1.  it  is  proved 
thing  is  according  to  substance,  but  from  hvpo-   !ihat  thT  Is  no 

,       P  .  ^1  demonstration 

thesis  assuming  that  the  very  nature  of  a  thing   ofthedefini- 
in  the  question  what  it  is,  is   something  of  its   S?pSjS£2 

1  Oil  Xiyti  6  fc/tXfyon'.  A  paronomasia;  a  definition  is  said  to  be 
selected  from  division,  because  not  all  the  members  of  the  division  are 
assumed  in  the  definition,  but  always  from  two  opposite  members,  the 
one  is  assumed  and  the  other  relinquished.     Taylor. 

2  That  is,  we  may  question  each  part  of  the  definition,  which  is  added 
successively,  e.  g.  why  is  man  animal  ?  why  mortal?  etc.  Trap'  iica<7T7]p 
irpoaOcoiv. 

3  Syllogism  here,  as  in  other  places  continually,  means  the  conclusion, 
and,  as  Waitz  remarks,  Aristotle  would  more  accurately  have  written 
d\\'  o  ovWoyia/iOQ  oi)%  opirr/xbg  ytverai.  Division  was  a  favourite  method 
with  Plato,  for  the  demonstration  of  definitions,  but  Aristotle  considers 
it  only  a  weak  kind  of  syllogism  ;  in  fact,  that  its  chief  use  is  to  test 
definitions  when  obtained.  Andronicus  Rhodius  wrote  a  separate  trea- 
tise on  division,  and  amongst  the  later  Peripatetics,  the  system  was  ap- 
parently held  in  higher  estimation.  Cf.  Cic.  Top.  en.  6;  Quintil.  v.  10; 
vii.  1  ;  Hamilton's  Keid ;  Trendelen.  Elem.  and  Abelaid  Dialectica,  ed. 
Cousin. 

Y   2 


324  aristotle's  organon.  [book  ii. 

defines  the  de-  peculiar  principles,  and  that  these  alone1  indicate 
finition  itself.  -^  substance,  and  that  the  whole2  is  its  peculiar- 
ity ?  for  this  is  its  essence.  Or  again,  has  a  person  assumed 
the  very  nature  of  a  thing  in  this  also  ?  for  we  must  neces- 
sarily demonstrate  through  a  middle  term.3  Moreover,  as  in 
a  syllogism,  we  do  not  assume  what  is  to  have  been  syllo- 
gistically  concluded,  (for  the  proposition  is  either  a  whole  or 
a  part,  from  which  the  syllogism  consists,)  thus  neither  ought 
the  very  nature  of  a  thing  to  be  in  a  syllogism,  but  this 
should  be  separate  from  the  things  which  are  laid  down,  and 
in  reply  to  him  who  questions  whether  this  has  been  syllo- 
gistically  concluded  or  not,  we  must  answer  that  it  is,  for  this 
was  the  syllogism.4  And  to  him  who  asserts  that  the  very 
nature  of  the  thing  was  not  concluded,  we  must  reply  that 
it  was,  for  the  very  nature  of  the  thing  was  laid  down  by  us, 
so  that  it  is  necessary  that  without  the  definition  of  syllogism, 
or  of  the  definition  itself,  something  should  be  syllogistically 
inferred. 

2  Nor  b  Also,  if  a  person  should  demonstrate  from  hy- 

other  hypotne-   pothesis,  for  instance,  if  to  be   divisible   i3  the 

ica  sy  ogism.   egsence  0f  evji .  ^ut  0f  a  contrary,  the  essence  is 

contrary  of  as  many  things  as  possess  a  contrary ;  but  good 
is  contrary  to  evil,  and  the  indivisible  to  the  divisible,  then 
the  essence  of  good  is  to  be  indivisible.  For  here  he  proves 
assuming  the  very  nature  of  a  thing,  and  he  assumes  it  in 
*  Therefore       order  to  demonstrate  what  is  its  very  nature :  * 

**  be°"S  the  • 

question."  cf.   let  however  something  be  different,  since  in  de- 

1  The  things  assumed  as  constituting  the  definition. 

2  The  composite  from  many  attributes.  It  may  be  observed  that  there 
are  two  ways  of  investigating  definition  ;  one  by  division,  and  the  other 
by  induction;  the  first  took  a  wide  genus,  including  the  object  to  be  de- 
fined, and  contracted  it  by  the  addition  of  successive  differentia?,  until  we 
obtain  a  complex  notion,  co-extensive  with  that  of  which  the  definition 
is  sought ;  this  was  Plato's  favourite  method,  though  rejected  by  Speusip- 
pus.  Vide  Scholia,  p.  179,  b.  xi.  The  other  method  was  by  induction, 
which  consisted  in  examining  the  several  individuals  of  which  the  term 
to  be  defined  is  predicable,  and  observing  what  they  have  in  common  ;  the 
definition  sought,  being  the  one  common  notion  which  is  thus  obtained. 
Vide  Mansel's  Logic,  Appendix  B. ;   Locke's  Essay,  book  ii.  ch.  23. 

3  The  medium  being  the  essence,  the  latter  is  thus  assumed  to  demon- 
strate itself. 

4  i.  e.  from  the  definition  of  syllogism,  it  must  be  shown  that  the  syllo- 
gism was  rightly  constructed,  and  the  conclusion  properly  inferred. 


CHAP.  VII.]  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS. 


325 


monstrations  k  is  assumed  that  this  is  predicated 
of  that,  yet  not  that  very  thing,  nor  that  of  which 
there  is  the  same  definition,*  and  which  recipro- 
cates.! To  both  however  there  is  the  same  doubt 
against  him  who  demonstrates  by  division,  and 
against  the  syllogism  thus  formed,  why  man  will 
be  an  animal  biped  pedestrian,1  but  not  an  ani- 
mal and  pedestrian,};  for  from  the  things  assumed, 
there  is  no  necessity  that  there  should  be  one 
predicate,  but  just  as  the  same  man  may  be  both 
a  musician  and  a  grammarian. § 


Prior.  An.  b. 
ii.  ch.  16. 

*  Equally  un- 
known as  the 
conclusion, 
t  When  the 
proposition  can 
be  equally- 
proved  by,  as 
prove  the  con- 
clusion. 
t  So  that  one 
thing  is  not 
proved  from 
these. 

§  Cf.  Interpre- 
tation, ch.  11. 


Chap.  VII. —  That  what  a  thing  is  can  neither  be  known  by  Demon- 
stration nor  by  Definition. 

How  then  will  he  who  defines  show  the  essence  ,    .„  ,„„, . 

i.  ah  inquiry 

of  a  thing,  or  what  it  is  ?  for  neither  as  demon-  into    the   me- 

strating  from  things  ||  which  are  granted  will  he  ingdetomon." 

render  it  evident  that  when  they  exist,  it  is  ne-  °blection.s: 

cessary  that  something  else^f  should  be,  for  de-  n  The  coneiu- 

monstration  is  this,  nor  as  forming  an  induction  Bion" 

by  singulars  which  are  manifest,  that  every  thing  thus  subsists, 

from  nothing  *  subsisting  otherwise  ;  since  he  does 

not  show  what  a  thing  is,  but  that  it  is,  or  is  not. 

What  remaining  method  is  there?  for  he  will  not 

indicate  by  sense  nor  by  the  finger. 

Moreover  how  will  he  show  what  it  t  is  ?  for  it  \-     „r  . 

,  '  t  So  Waitz  and 

is  necessary  that  he  also  who  knows  what  man  is,  Rekker.  Buhie 

or  any  thing  else,  should  also  know  that  he  is,2  %  for  fead^hat1, 

no  one  knows  with  respect  to  non-being  that  it  is,  " ™an" is. 

but  what  the  definition  or  the  name  signifies,  as  chapte"?* 
when    I   say  "tragehiphos,"   it  is  impossible   to 


*  No  indi- 
vidual. 


n 


1  So  that  one  thing  is  produced  from  these,  according  to  the  nature  of 
definition.    Cf.  on  Interpretation,  ch.  5. 

2  Before  we  can  determine  the  real  definition  of  any  object  (n  tort) 
we  must  of  necessity  ascertain  that  it  exists  (on  fori).  (Vide  next  chap- 
ter.) Now  the  existence  of  attributes  and  that  of  substances  being  de- 
termined in  two  different  ways,  there  is  a  corresponding  variety  in  the 
form  of  definition,  the  former  being  defined  by  the  same  cause  which 
served  as  a  middle  term  to  prove  their  existence,  a  mode  of  definition 
described  as  frvWoyiVfibg  tov  Tt  tort,  HTWOtl  fiatyipujv  ri}<;  AiroCli%lW£ — 
four  causes  being  recognised  by  Aristotle  (cf.  An.  Vunt.  b.  ii.  en.  11)  :  but 


326  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  n. 

know  what  tragelaphos  is.  Moreover,  if  he  should  show  what 
a  thing  is,  and  that  it  is,  how  will  he  show  this  in  the  same 
sentence  ?  for  both  definition  and  also  demonstration  manifest 
one  certain  thing,  but  what  man  is  is  one  thing,  and  the  es- 
sence of  man  is  another. 

We  next  say  that  it  is  necessary  to  show  by 
not"t^SeSsub-S  demonstration  every  thing,  that  it  is,  except  it  be 
stance  to  any  substance,  but  to  be,  is  not  SLibstar.ee  to  any  thing, 
for  being  is  not  the  genus.  There  will  then  be 
tionof"what"  demonstration  that  it  is,*  and  this  the  sciences 
'tis.  now  effect.     For  ivhat  a  triangle  means,  the  geo- 

metrician  assumes,  but  that  it  is,  he  demonstrates.       What 
then   will   he  who  defines  what  it  is,  prove?    that  it    is   a 
...     triangle  ?    he    then    who  knows    what   it  is    by 

+   Fecause  it  is  &,  .„  .     ,     ,  ,  .       ! 

not  yet  chosen   definition,  will  not   know  ll   it  is,j  but  this  IS 

to  be  a  triangle.    impossible. 

4.  Error  of  Evidently  then  those  who  define  according  to 

present  modes.   tbe  present  methods  of  definition,  do  not  demon- 
strate that  a  thing  is,  for  although  those  lines  be  equal  which 
are    drawn    from  the   middle,   yet  why  is  it  the  thing  de- 
.       drc]e     fined  ?  \  and  why  is  this  a  circle  ?  §  for  we  might 
§  wV  "is™  he   say  that  there  is  the  same  definition  of  brass.  ||    For 
circle  a  figure   neitiier  do  definitions  demonstrate  that  it  is  possi- 
lines  from  the   ble  for  that  to  be  which  is  asserted,  nor  that  that 
drnu!mfetrenchee   thing  is,  of  which  they  say  there  are  definitions,1 
ll  ope.x«Ax™.     \yUt  it,  is  always  possible  to  say  why.^f 
rog'ate',  why  Ys       If  then  he  who  defines  shows  either  what  a 
this  a  circle.       thing  is  or  what  the  name  signifies,  except  there 
is,  by  no  means  (an  explanation)  of  what  a  thing 
is,  definition  will  be  a  sentence  signifying  the  same 
thing  as  a  name,  but  this  is  absurd. 2     For  in  the  first  place 

the  definition  of  substances  is  determined  by  the  formal  cause,  in  refer- 
ence to  the  essential  constituents  of  the  general  notion,  the  possession  of 
which  entitles  the  individual  to  be  reckoned  under  it.  Aristotle  makes 
summa  genera,  and  individuals  alone  indefinite.  Locke  avers  that  simple 
ideas  only  cannot  be  defined.  Cf.  Metap.  books  vi.  and  x. ;  Locke's  Essay, 
b.  iii.  4,  7;  Descarte's  Princip.  i.  10;  Occam's  Logic,  Part  I. 

1  Definition  does  not  teach  that  the  proposed  thing,  the  essence  of 
which  is  investigated,  exists  in  the  nature  of  things,  nor  does  it  teach  that 
the  thing  is  that,  the  essence  of  which  the  definition  unfolds.     Taylor. 

1  Cf.  Top.  vi.  4  and  6,  14;  Metap.  vi.  11;  Albert  de  Praed.  Tract,  i. : 
Occam,  Part  I.  eh.  26 ;  Whately's  Logic,  and  Aldrich  upon  nominal  and 


CHAP.    VIII.]  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS. 


327 


there  would  be  a  definition  of  non-essences  and  of  non-entities, 
since  it  is  possible  even  for  non-entities  to  have  a  signification. 
Again,  all  sentences  will  be  definitions,  for  we  might  give  a 
name  to  any  sentence,  so  that  we  might  all  discuss  in  definitions, 
and  the  Iliad  would  be  a  definition.  Besides,  no  science  would 
demonstrate  that  this  name  signifies  this  thing,  neither  there- 
fore do  definitions  manifest  this. 

From  these  things  therefore  it  appears  that 
neither  definition  nor  syllogism  are  the  same 
thing,  nor  are  syllogism  and  definition  of  the  same 
thing,  moreover  that  definition  neither  demon- 
strates nor  shows  any  thing,  and  that  we  can 
know  what  a  thing  is  neither  by  definition  nor  by 
demonstration. 


6.  Recapitula- 
tion.    It  is 
proved  that  we 
can  know 
'■  quid  res  sit 
neither  by  de- 
finition nor  by 
demonstration. 


Chap.  VIII. — Of  the  logical  Syllogism  of  what  a  thing  is. 

Moreover  we  must  consider  which  of  these  j  QUestion„ 
things  is  well,  and  which  is  not  well  asserted,  also  propounded  tor 
what  definition  is,  and  whether  there  is  in  a  consi  eratlon- 
certain  way  or  by  no  means  a  demonstration  and  definition  of 
what  a  thing  is.  Now  since  it  is  the  same  thing  as  we  have 
said  to  know  what  a  thing  is,  and  to  know  the  cause  where- 
fore *  it  is,  and  the  reason  of  this  is,  that  there  is  a 
certain  cause,  f  and  this  is  either  the  same  or 
another,  \  and  if  it  is  another,  it  is  either  demon- 
strable or  indemonstrable  ;  if  then  it  is  another,  and 
is  capable  of  demonstration,1  it  is  necessary  that 
the  cause  should  be  a  medium,  and  should  be  de- 
monstrated in  the  first  figure,  for  that  which  is 
demonstrated  is  both  universal  and  affirmative. § 
Now  one  method  will  be  that  which  has  been  now 
investigated,  viz.  to  demonstrate  what  a  thing  is 
through  something  else,  for  of  those  things  which 


*    uniov  TOV  T 
eanv.  Cf.  ch.  2. 
t  Essentiae  rei. 
I  Different 
from  the  es- 
sence of  whict 
it  is  the  cause. 


§  i.  e.   the  n? 
ture  of  a  thing 
is  universally 
affirmed  of  that 
of  which   it  is 
the  nature. 


reai  definition.  It  will  be  found  from  various  places  cited,  that  physical 
definition  was  rejected  by  Aristotle,  and  that  nominal  definition  is  one  in 
which  the  existence  of  the  objects  to  which  the  definition  is  applicable  is 
not  proved;  in  fact,  it  is  questionable  whether  the  name  "  nominal  defini- 
tion "  is  sanctioned  by  Aristotle  (Cf.  Trendelen.  Elem.  55,  upon  ch.  10 
of  this  book,  and  Mansel,  Appendix  B. 

1  If  being  different  from  the  "  what"  a  thing  ia,  it  can  be  demonstrated 
"  what"  it  is. 


328 


Aristotle's  organon. 


[book  II. 


are  predicated  in  respect  of  what  a  thing  is,  it  is 
necessary  that  the  medium  should  be  what  it  is, 
lightf  defectof  and  a  property  in  respect  of  properties,  wherefore 
of  two  essential  natures  of  the  same  thing,*  it  will 
demonstrate  the  one,f  but  not  the  other.| 

That  this  method  then  is  not  demonstration,  has 
been  shown  before,  but  it  is  a  logical  syllogism  of 
what  a  thing  is,  still  let  us  show  in  what  method 
this  is  possible,  discussing  it  again  from  the  be- 
ginning. For  as  we  investigate  why  a  thing  is, 
when  we  know  that  it  is,  but  sometimes  those 
become  evident  at  the  same  time,  but  it  is  not 
possible  to  know  why  it  is,  prior  to  knowing  that 
"  what  a  thing  it  is,  it  is  clear  that  in  like  manner  the  very  nature 
andknown?16*1  of  a  tning>  or  what  it  is,  cannot  be  known,  with- 
out knowing  that  it  is,  since  it  is  impossible  to 
know  what  a  thing  is,  when  ignorant  if  it  is.§ 
We  sometimes  indeed  know  if  it  is,  accidentally, 
knowing  sometimes  something  belonging  to  the 
thing,1  as  thunder  we  know,  because  it  is  a  cer- 
tain sound  of  the  clouds,  and  an  eclipse,  because  it  is  a  eer"- 


•  e.  g.  an 
eclipse. 


t  e.  g.  the  op 
position  of  the 
earth. 

2.  The  logical 
syllogism  "  de 
eo,  quid  sit." 
The  "why" 
and  the  "  that" 
sometimes  si- 
multaneously 
known.    The 
"  if"  some- 
times known. 
Kara  avtifie- 
3riKor.     How 


§  Vide  last 
chapter :  other- 
wise   the   defi- 
nition   will  be 
only  nominal. 


1  This  passage  is  doubtful :  it  has  nevertheless  been  used  for  the  de- 
cision of  the  question  as  to  whether  the  class  of  definitions  described  as 
rrjg  tov  ri  ioriv  aTroSti^aog  avfiirepaapa,  is  to  be  regarded  as  nominal,  or 
as  imperfect  real  definition  ;  the  question  is  of  less  importance  as  Aris- 
totle elsewhere  condemns  their  use  (De  Anima  ii.  2,  2).  The  instances  he 
gives  here  may  refer  either  to  the  one  or  the  other  description.  The 
authorities  who  hold  the  first  view  of  the  subject  are  Averroes,  Zabarella 
and  St.  Hilaire ;  those  who  hold  up  their  pens  "  on  the  contrary,"  are  the 
Greek  commentators,  Pacius,  Rassow,  and  Kuhn. 

B  A 

That  to  which  the  earth  is  opposed  is  eclipsed. 

B  C 

The  earth  is  opposed  to  the  moon. 

C  A 

The  moon  is  eclipsed. 


Ex.  1. 


Ex.  2. 


B 

What  does  not  produce  a  shadow  when  nothing  intervenes  u 

A 
eclipsed. 

C  B 

The  moon  does  not  produce  a  shadow,  &c» 

C  A 

The  moon  is  eclipsed. 


CHAP,  vm.]  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  329 

tain  privation  of  light,  and  a  man,  because  it  is  a  certain 
animal,  and  soul,  because  it  moves  itself.  As  regards  then 
whatever  we  know  accidentally  that  they  are,  it  is  by  no  means 
necessary  that  we  should  possess  any  thing  by  which  to  know 
what  they  are,  for  neither  do  we  (really)  know  that  they  are, 
and  to  inquire  what  a  thing  is,  when  we  do  not  know  that  it 
is,  is  to  inquire  about  nothing.  In  those  things  however  of 
which  we  know  something,  it  is  easy  (to  inquire)  what  they 
are  ;  hence  as  Ave  know  that  a  thing  is,  so  also  are  we  disposed 
to  know  what  it  is,  now  of  those  things,  of  whose  essential 
nature  we  know  something,  let  this  be  first  an  example,  an 
eclipse  A,  the  moon  C,  the  opposition  of  the  earth   „  _, 

t»  *       m     •  •  i  1       i  i  •  i>  Example  (1.) 

B.        lo  inquire  then  whether  there  is  an  eclipse 
or  not,  is  to  inquire  whether  B  is  or  not,  but  this  does  not 
at  all  differ  from  the  inquiry  if  there  is  a  reason  of  it,  and  if 
this  is,  we  say  that  that  also  is.     Or  we  (inquire)  of  which  con- 
tradiction there  is  a  reason,  whether  of  possessing,  or  of  not 
possessing,  two  right  angles,  but  when  we  have  discovered, 
we  know  at  the  same  time,  that  it  is,  and   why  it  is,  if  it  is 
inferred  through  media  ;f  but  if  it  is  not  so  in-    +  SoBekker 
ferred,  we  know  the  that,  but  not  the  why.     Let   Buhie,  and 
C  be  the  moon,  A  an  eclipse,  not  to  be  able  to   w^tz'a»,U 


aue- 

<JWV. 


produce  a  shadow  when  the  moon  is  full  and 
nothing  is  seen  interposed  between  us,  B,  if  then  B,  that  is,  not 
to  be  able  to  produce  a  shadow  when  there  is  nothing  be- 
tween us,  be  present  with  C,  and  A,  to  be  eclipsed,  present 
with  this,  that  there  is  an  eclipse,  is  indeed  evident,  but  why  is 
not  yet  so,  and  that  there  is  an  eclipse,  we  indeed  know,  but 
what  it  is  we  do  not  know.t     Yet  as  it  is  clear    ^  „        ,  ,„ . 

.  .     r~.     ,  .    \       ,       .     .  .  1  Example  (2.) 

that  A  is  with  C,  (to  inquire)  why  it  is,  is  to  in- 
vestigate what  B  is,  whether  it  is  the  opposition  (of  the 
earth),  or  the  turn  of  the  moon,  or  the  extinction  of  light, 
but  this  is  the  definition  of  the  other  extreme,  as  in  those 
(examples)  of  A,  since  an  eclipse  is  the  interposition  of  the 
earth.  What  is  thunder  ?  the  extinction  of  fire  in  a  cloud : 
why  does  it  thunder  ?    because   fire   is    extinguished   in  a 

B  A 

Ex.  3.  Where  there  is  an  extinction  of  fire  there  is  thunder. 
C  B 

In  a  cloud  there  is  extinction  of  fire. 
C  A 

. '  .  In  %  cloud  there  is  thunder. 


330  akistotle's  organon.  [book  n. 

cloud.     Let   C  be  a  cloud,  A  thunder,  B  the  extinction  of 

fire,  hence  B  is  present  with  C,  that  is,  with  the  cloud,  for 

fire  is  extinguished  in  it,  but  A,  sound,  is  present 

*  ^"another     wittl  thiS'   and  B  *S   the  definition  °f    A'  tlle    firSt 

prio/cause  of  extreme ;  *  if  there  be  again  another  medium  of 
ofeth°ePearth.0n     this  "f  it  will  be  from  the  remaining  definitions.1 

of  what  a  ^e  kave  snown  therefore  thus,  how  what  a 

thing  Z,  the™  thing  is,  is  assumed,  and  becomes  known,  where- 
logism  "or  de-"  fore  there  is  neither  syllogism  nor  demonstration 
monstration,  0f  what  a  thing  is,  still  it  will  become  evident 
festeVbyTolh.  through  syllogism,  and  through  demonstration; 
cf.  ch.  3.  an(j   nence  without  demonstration  it  is  neither 

possible  to  know  what  a  thing  is,  of  which  there  is  another 
cause,  nor  is  there  demonstration  of  it,  as  we  have  already 
observed  in  the  doubts. 


Chap.  IX. — Of  certain  Natures  or  Principles  incapable  of 
Demonstration. 

i.  a  two-fold  Of  some  things  indeed  there  is  a  certain  other 
division  of  cause,  but  of  others  there  is  not,  so  that  it  is  plain 
method  used  that  some  of  them  are  immediate,  and  principles, 
in  each.  whose  existence  and  what  they  are,  we  must  sup- 

pose, or  make  manifest  after  another  manner,2  which  indeed 
the  arithmetician  does,  for  he  both  supposes  what  unity  is, 
and  that  it  is.  Of  those  however  which  have  a  medium,3  and  of 
whose  essence  there  is  another  cause,  it  is  possible,  as  we  have 
said,  to  produce  a  manifestation  through  demonstration,  yet 
not  by  demonstrating  what  they  are. 

1  Sin  autem  etiam  alius  terminus  medius  inveniri  potest  per  quem  co- 
gatur  propositio  A  B,  is  quoque  una  ex  reliquis  definitionibus  notionis  A 
non  esse  non  poterit.  Waitz.  If  what  a  thing  is,  may  be  proved  by 
another  what,  this  last  may  also  be  proved  by  another,  so  that  there  will 
be  three  causes  of  an  eclipse,  of  which  the  1st  proves  the  2nd,  and  the 
2nd  the  3rd,  and  if  all  are  joined  there  will  be  a  perfect  definition.  Cf. 
ch.  10. 

2  As  by  induction,  or  a  demonstration  of  the  "  that."  He  shows  here 
that  definitions  are  assumed  prior  to  all  demonstration,  and  are  real,  in- 
asmuch as  the  existence  of  the  objects  is  assumed  with  them.  The 
ground  of  the  assumption  will  vary  according  to  the  nature  of  the  object 
to  be  defined.    Cf.  Metap.  x.  7. 

3  A  cause  different  from  themselves. 


CHAP.  X.  THE    POSTERIOR  ANALYTICS.  331 


Chap.  X. —  Upon  Definition  and  its  kinds. 

Since   definition  is  said  to  be  a  sentence  (ex-    ]   Definition 
planatory)  of  what  a  thing  is,  it  is  evident  that   either  explains 
one  definition  will  be  of  what  a  name  signifies,  or   Jjj™16  of  a 
another  nominal  sentence,  as  what  a  thing  signi- 
fies, which  is  so  far  as  it  is  a  triangle,  which  when  we  know 
that  it  is,  we  inquire  why  it  is.1      Still  it  is  difficult  thus  to 
assume  things,  the  existence  of  which  we  do  not  know,  and 
the  cause  ofthis  difficulty  has  been  explained  before,  because 
neither  do  we  know  whether  it  is  or  is  not,  except  accidentally. 
One  sentence  is  indeed  in  two  ways,  the  one  by  conjunction, 
as  the  Iliad,  but  the  other  from  signifying  one  thing  of  one, 
not  accidentally. 

The  above-named  then  is  one  definition  of  a   2  0r  shows  its 
definition,  but  the  other  definition  is  a  sentence   <?use.   a  dis- 

.  .  if-  Unction  drawn. 

showing  why  a  thing  is,  so  -that  the  iormer 
signifies,  but  does  not  demonstrate,  but  the  lattei  will  evi- 
dently be,  as  it  were,  a  demonstration  of  what  a  thing  is,  dif- 
fering from  demonstration  in  the  position  (of  the  terms).  For 
there  is  a  difference  between  saying,  why  does  it  thunder  ?  and 
what  is  thunder  ?  for  thus  a  person  will  answer,  because  fire 
is  extinguished  in  the  clouds  ;  but  what  is  thunder  ?  the  sound 
of  fire  extinguished  in  the  clouds ;  hence  there  is  the  same 
sentence  spoken  in  another  manner,  and  in  the  one  way  there 
is  a  continued  demonstration,  but  in  the  other  there  is  a  de- 

1  Vide  Aldrich,  Hill's  and  Whately's  Logics  upon  nominal  and  real 
definition.  With  regard  to  the  expression  \oyoe  inpog,  opo^arwdtjg, 
(oratio  diversa  nominalis,  Buhle.)  Trendelenburg's,  (Elementa,  55,)  the 
literal  rendering,  gives  the  idea  that  nominal  as  well  as  real  defini- 
tions must  be  sentences,  but  Manse]  thinks  the  context  seems  rather  to 
mean  "  a  definition  of  the  signification  of  a  name,  or  of  another  sentence 
having  the  force  of  a  name ; "  yet  on  the  other  hand  fairly  allows  that  in 
this  wav  the  word  crtpog  "  is  superfluous,"  and  the  example  given  "  un- 
intelligible." There  is  no  doubt  therefore  that  by  Xoyoc  ovofiarw^rtq  is 
meant  a  sentence  whose  signification,  like  that  of  a  single  noun,  is  one ; 
a  description  which  includes  all  real  definitions,  of  which  the  example  is 
a  specimen.  We  subjoin  the  places  he  refers  to  :  Int.  v.  "2  ;  Metap.  vi.  4, 
and  1'2,  and  vii.  6;  Alex.  Scholia,  p.  743,  a.  31.  In  the  Greek  com- 
mentators \6yog  ovofi.  is  clearly  used  for  nominal  definitions  :  see  Philop. 
Schol.  p.  211,  b.  31,  also  Mansel,  Appendix  B.  p.  19.  For  the  differ- 
ent uses  of  the  word  Aoyoc.  by  Aristotle,  as  en.jnciative  of  definition,  cf. 
Waitz  upon  this  chapter. 


332  ARISTOTLE  S    ORG  ANON.  [BOOK    n. 

finition.     Moreover  the  definition  of  thunder  is,  a  sound  in 
the  clouds,  but  this  is  the  conclusion  of  the  de- 
ckle also8'        monstration  of  what  it  is;  now  the  definition  of 
Mansei's Logic,   things  immediate  is,  the  indemonstrable  thesis  of 

page  16,  App.  *  i     . 

note.)  essence.*1 

3.  Brief  sum-  One  definition  then  is,  an  indemonstrable  sen- 
forms~ fdefini  *ence  (significative)  of  essence,  but  another  is  a 
tion.  syllogism  of  essence,  differing  from  demonstration 
t  i.  e.  in  in  case,  j  and  a  third  is  the  conclusion  of  the  de- 
form, or  in  the  monstration  of  what  a  thing  is.  Wherefore,  from 
position  of  the  wnat  we  have  said,  it  is  evident  how  there  is,  and 

terms. 

how  there  is  not,  a  demonstration  of  what  a  thing 
is,  also  of  what  things  there  is,  and  of  what  there  is  not ;  more- 
over in  how  many  ways  definition  is  enunciated,  and  how  it 
demonstrates  the  essence  of  a  thing,  and  how  it  does  not ;  also 
of  what  things  there  is,  and  of  what  there  is  not,  definition  ; 
yet  more,  how  it  subsists  with  respect  to  demonstration,  and 
how  it  may,  and  how  it  may  not  be,  of  the  same  thing. 


Chap.  XI. — Of  Causes  and  their  Demonstration. 

l.  Causes  of  Since  we  think  that  we  scientifically  know, 
wWcliareaTi'1'  wnen  we  are  cognizant  of  the  cause,  but  causes 
expressed  by      are  four,2  one   indeed   as   to   the   essence  of  a 

1  "  Of  things  immediate,"  such  as  the  definition  of  a  subject.  Waitz 
and  Pacius  consider  Trraxrig  and  Qeoig  synonymous.  Upon  the  kinds  of 
definition  referred  to  here,  the  reader  will  find  ample  information  in 
Mansel's  Appendix  B.,  where  they  are  ably  and  fully  discussed. 

2  Upon  the  four  causes  of  things,  see  Forchhammer  Verhandlungen  der 
sechsten,  Versammlung  deutscher  Philoll.  und  Schulmm.  Cassel,  1344, 
p.  84 — 89.  Although  Aristotle  allows  any  of  the  four  to  be  used  as  a  mid- 
dle term,  yet  it  by  no  means  follows  that  each  may  be  a  definition  of 
the  major,  for  while  he  has  not  decidedly  expressed  his  opinion,  it  is 
probable  that  he  regarded  the  formal  cause  only,  as  available  for  defini- 
tion. For  not  only  has  a  material  cause  no  place  in  attributes,  but  in 
physical  substances  (Metap.  vii.  4) ;  in  this  chapter  he  gives  a  material 
cause,  instanced  as  a  middle  term,  as  in  fact  identical  with  the  formal. 
The  efficient  and  final  causes  seem,  as  Mansel  says,  to  be  excluded,  as 
not  being  contemporaneous  with  their  effects,  so  that  from  the  existence 
ot  the  one  we  cannot  certainly  infer  that  of  the  other.  Vide  Waitz,  vol. 
ii.  p.  41 1 ;  Trendelenburg,  de  Anim.  p.  355 ;  Mansel,  App.  B.  17.  Cf.  also 
next  chapter;  Metap.  books  vi.,  xi.,  xii.,  xiii. ;  De  Anim.i. ;  Physic,  lib. 
i.  and  ii. 


CHAP.  XI.]  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS. 


333 


the  middle 
term. 

*   TO  t*  rjv  t'ivut 

— the  formal 
cause. 

t  The  material 
cause. 

:  The  efficient 
cause. 
§  The  final. 
||  When  one  of 
these  is  as- 
sumed for  a 
middle.     (Vide 
note.) 
IT  The  middle. 


*  Vide  Euclid, 
b.  iii.  prop.  31. 


thin":  *  another  that  which  from  certain  tilings  ex- 
isting,  this  necessarily  exists,  f  a  third  that  which 
first  moves  something,}  and  a  fourth  on  account  of 
which  a  thing  (exists) ;  §  all  these  are  demonstrated 
through  a  medium. ||  For  the  one  that  this  existing 
it  is  necessary  that  that  should  be,  is  not  from 
one  proposition  being  assumed,  but  from  two  at 
the  least,  but  this  is,  when  they  have  one  medium  ; 
this  one  therefore  being  assumed,^  there  is  neces- 
sarily a  conclusion,  which  is  evidently  thus  :  Why 
is  the  angle  a  right  one  in  a  semicircle,  or  from 
the  existence  of  what,  is  it  right  ?  *  Let  then  A  be 
a  right  angle,  B  the  half  of  two  right  angles,  and 
the  angle  in  the  semicircle  C.  Hence  B  is  the  cause  why  A 
the  right  angle  is  inherent  in  C,  i.  e.  in  the  angle  of  a  semi- 
circle ;  for  this  angle  is  equal  to  A,  but  C  is  equal  to  B,  for  it 
is  the  half  of  two  right  angles  ;  B  then  being  the  half  of  two 
right  angles,  A  is  inherent  in  C,  and  this  was  for 
the  angle  in  a  semicircle  to  be  a  right  angle. f  +  Example  0.) 
This!  however  is  the  same  as  the  explanation  of  *. The  concIu- 

n  i  sion. 

the  essence  of  a  thing,  §  because  definition  signifies    §  Because  a 
this,  but  the  cause  of  the  essence  of  a  thing  has   samfas  Us  na- 
been  shown  to  be  the  middle.  ||    Why  was  there  a   tur,e- 
Median  war  with  the  Athenians  ?    What  was  the 
cause  of  waging  war  with  the  Athenians  ?  Because  the  latter 
with  the  Eretrians  attacked  Sardis  ;  this  was  the  first  cause  of  the 
movement.     Let  war  then  be  A,  first  made  the  attack  B,  the 
Athenians  C,  B  then  is  present  with  C,  i.  e.  to  have  first  made 
the  attack  is  present  with  the  Athenians,  but  A  is  also  with  B, 
for  they  make  war  with  the  aggressors,  A  then  is  present  with 
B,  i.  e.  to  wage  war  is  present  with  the  aggressors,  but  this,  B, 
is  present  with  the  Athenians,  for  they  were  the  aggressors. 
Wherefore  the  middle  is  the  cause  here,  and  that  which  first 
moves  ;  but  of  those  things,  whose  cause  is  for  the  sake  of  some- 
thing, as,  why  does  he  walk  ?  that  he  may  be  well  ■  why  is  a 

B  A 

Ex.  1.  Every  angle  which  is  the  half  of  two  right  angles  is  a  right  angle 

C  B 

Every  angle  described  in  a  semicircle  is  the  half  of  two  right 
angles 

C  A 

.  " .  Every  angle  described  in  a  semicircle  is  a  right  angle. 


334  Aristotle's  organox.  [book  ii. 

house  built  ?  that  furniture  may  be  preserved ;  the  one  is  for 
the  sake  of  health,  but  the  other  for  the  sake  of  preservation. 
Still  there  is  no  difference  between  why  is  it  necessary  to 
walk  after  supper,  and  for  the  sake  of  what  is  it  necessary  ? 
but  let  walking  after  supper  be  C,  the  food  not  to  rise  B,  to 
be  well  A.  Let  then  walking  after  supper  be  the  cause  why 
the  food  does  not  rise  to  the  mouth  of  the  stomach,  and  let 
this  be  healthy  ;  for  B,  that  is,  for  the  food  not  to  rise,  appears 
to  be  present  with  walking,  C,  and  with  this  A,  salubrious. 
What  then  is  the  cause  that  A,  which  is  that  for  the  sake  of 
which  (the  final  cause),  is  present  with  C  ?  B  (is 
the  cause),  that  is,  the  food  not  rising,  this  *  how- 
X  Example  (2.)  ever  is  as  **  were> the  definition  of  it,f  for  A  will 
§  The  premises  be  thus  explained.1 1  Why  is  B  present  with  C? 
*nExamp"e  u"'  because  to  be  thus  affected  is  to  be  well :  we  must 
it  in  final         nevertheless  change  the  sentences,  &  and  thus  the 

causes.  ,  ,°  ?3 

*  Efficient  several  points  will  be  more  clear. ||     The  genera- 

tTnttie  latter.  tions  ^ere  ^  indeed,  and  in  causes  respecting  mo- 

t  The  cause,  tion,*  subsist  vice  versa,  for  there  f  it  is  necessary 

t  TnTeffect5.6'  that  the  middle  if  should  be  first  generated,  but 

jr  The  last  in  here  S  C,  which  is  the  last,||  and  that  for  the  sake 

ti  me,  not  in  P      ,■'.    .     .  , " 

nature.  or  which  is  generated  the  last.lf 

2  The  same  Possibly  indeed  the  same  thing  may  be  for  the 

thing  may  sake  of  something,  and  from  necessity ;  for  instance, 
sesTtwocS;  wh7  does  Mght  pass  through  a  lantern?  for  ne- 
cessarily that  which  consists  of  smaller  particles 
passes  through  larger  pores,  if  light  is  produced  by  transit,  also 
(it  does  so)  on  account  of  something,  that  we  may  not  fall.  If 
then  it  possibly  may  be,  is  it  also  possible  to  be  generated  ? 

1  That  is,  the  healthy  will  be  explained  to  be  that  which  does  not  suf- 
fer the  food  to  rise. 

B  A 

Ex.  2.  For  the  food  not  to  rise  in  the  stomach  is  healthy 
C  B 

Walking  after  supper  does  not  suffer  the  food  to  rise,  ettv 
C  A 

. ' .  Walking  after  supper  is  healthy. 

A  B 

Ei.  3.  That  which  is  healthy  causes  the  food  not  to  rise 
C  A 

Walking  after  supper  is  healthy 

C  B 

.  * .  Walking  after  supper  causes  the  food  not  to  rise. 


CHAP.  XII.]  THE   POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  335 

as  if  it  thunders,  fire  being  extinguished,  it  is  necessary  that 
it  should  crash  and  rumble,  and,  as  the  Pythagoreans  say,  for 
the  sake  of  threatening,  that  those  in  Tartarus  may  be  terri- 
fied. Now  there  are  many  things  of  this  kind,  3  Necessity  is 
especially  in  those  which  are  constituted  and  con-   two-foid;  in- 

.  •  stances      Cf 

sist  from  nature,  for  nature  produces  one  thing    Rhet.  i.  11. 
for  the  sake   of  something*  and  another  from   *.?°rthe,sake 

.  ° '  of  the  end  or 

necessity;]"  but  necessity  is  two-told,  one  accord-    form. 

ing  to  nature  and  impulse,!  another  with  violence,    of1matter.eSSlty 

contrary  to  impulse  ;  thus  a  stone  is  borne  from    t  opm'j,  i.  e. 

.        i     .1  i  !i  i  natural  im- 

necessity  both  upward   and  downward,   yet  not   pu]Se. 
from  the   same  necessity.  S     In   things   however   §  Because  it 

m  descends  na- 

which  are  from  reason,  ||  some  never  subsist  irom   turaiiy,  but 
chance,  as  a  house,  or  a  statue,  nor  from  neces-    J1  Artificial06' 
sity,1  but  for  the  sake  of  something,  whilst  others   things, 
are   also  from   fortune,   as  health  and  safety.2  ^[   ir  cf.  Poetics, 
Especially  in  those  which  are  capable  of  a  various   ch' 9' 
subsistence,  as  when  the  generation  of  them  is  not  from  for- 
tune, so   that  there  is  a  good  end,    on  account   of  which  it 
takes  place,  and  either  by  nature  or  by  art :  from  fortune 
however  nothing  is  produced  for  the  sake  of  something. 


Chap.  XII. —  Upon  the  causes  of  the  Present,  Past,    (Cf.  Phys.  lib. 
and  Future.  iv) 

TnE  cause  of  things  which  are,  is  the  same  also    1.  identity  of 
as   that  of  things   which   are  generated,   which   cause- 
have  been  generated,  and  which  will  be,  for  the  middle  is  the 
cause,  except  that  being  is  the  cause  to  be,  what  is  generated, 
to  those  which  are  generated,  what  has  been,  to  those  which 

1  Not  from  the  necessity  of  matter ;  because  though  there  are  wood, 
stones,  and  cement,  yet  there  is  no  necessity  on  that  account  that  there 
should  be  a  house. 

2  "  As  health,"  which  is  either  from  the  medicinal  art,  or  from  chance, 
e.  g.  when  Pheraeus  Jason  was  healed  by  a  dart  thrown  by  an  enemy,  as 
Cicero  relates  in  book  hi.,  de  Naturft  Deorum  ;  "and  safety,"  which  so 
happens  to  a  ship  when  it  is  preserved,  either  on  account  of  the  art  and 
skill  of  the  pilot,  or  fortuitously.  Taylor.  Upon  necessity,  chance,  and 
the  principles  generally  alluded  to  at  the  close  of  this  chapter,  cf.  Phy- 
sics, book  ii. ;  Metaph.  books  iv.  v;  Rhet.  i.  6  (Bohn's  ed.,  where  see 
note) ;  also  i.  10,  and  Ethics  i.  9.  See  also  Montaigne's  Essays,  pp.  50 
and  105,  Hazlitt's  ed. 


336  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  ii. 

have  been,  and  what  will  be  to  those  that  will  be.  Thus  why 
was  there  an  eclipse  ?  because  the  earth  was  interposed,  but 
an  eclipse  is  generated,  because  an  interposition  of  the  earth 
is  generated,  but  there  will  be,  because  the  earth  will  be,  and 
there  is,  because  it  is  interposed.  What  is  ice  ?  Let  it  be  as- 
sumed to  be  congealed  water ;  let  water  be  C,  congealed  A, 
the  middle  cause  B,  a  perfect  defect  of  heat ;  B  then  is  pre- 
sent with  C,  but  with  this  A,  viz.  to  be  congealed,* 
but  ice  is  generated,  when  B  is  generated,  it  was 
so,  when  the  latter  was  so,  and  it  will  be,  when  the  latter 
will  be. 

2.  Causes  and  Hence  that  which  is  thus  a  cause,  and  that  of 
simultaneous17  which  it  is  the  cause,  are  generated  at  one  and 
—an  inquiry  the  same  time,  when  they  are  generated  ;  are  si- 
thin  grot's?-  multaneously  when  they  are ;  and  in  like  man- 
muitaneous.  ner?  jn  respect  to  the  having  been,  and  the  will 
be,  generated.  In  the  case  of  things  which  are  not  simul- 
taneous, are  there  in  a  continued  time,  as  it  seems  to  us,  dif- 
ferent causes  of  different  things  ?  for  instance,  is  another  thing 
having  been  generated  the  cause  of  this  thing  having  been 
generated,  and  another  thing  which  will  be,  the  cause  that 
this  will  be,  and  of  this  being,  something  which  was  generated 
before  ?  the  syllogism  however  is  from  what  was 
eluded  the  afterwards  generated.!  And  the  principle  of  these 
foundation  was   are   those   things  which    have    been   generated, 

laid  from  the  ,  _  b  .         ,  °  .  .        ' 

house  being  wherefore  the  case  is  the  same  as  to  things 
3UTheposte-  which  are  generated.  From  the  prior  indeed 
rior  not  col-       there  is  no  (syllogism),  as  that  this  thing  was 

lected  from  the       P,  -,        \  •/       o         / 

prior.  atterwards    generated,    because   that   thing   was 

I  That  because  generated, I  it  is  the  same  also  in  regard  to  the 

was  laid  the  future.     For  whether  the  time  be  indefinite  or 

house  was  definite, §  it  will  not  result  that  because  that  thing 

§  That  is,  the  was  truly  said  to  have  been  generated,  this  which 

tweeruie6  is  posterior  is  truly  said  to  have  been  generated. 

B  A 

Ex.  1.  That,  the  heat  of  which  fails,  is  congealed 
B  C 

The  heat  fails  of  water 
C  A 

.    .  Water  is  congealed. 


CHAP.  XII.]  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS. 


337 


since  in  the  interval  it  will  be  false  to  say  this,1    former  and  the 
when  already  another  thing*  has  been  produced.   |^ner eenera- 
The  same  reasoning  also  happens  to  what  will  be,   *  The  founda- 
nor  because  that  f  was  produced,  will  this  |  be,  as   t'°The  founda- 
the  middle  must  be  generated  at  the  same  time;2  V°.{?nehouse 
of  things  that  have  been  that  which  has  been,    4.  Medium 
of  the  future  the  future,  of  what  are  produced   [anfou^with11' 
that  which    is    produced,   of  things  which    are   those  of  which 
that  which  is,  but  of  what  was  generated,  and  of  dium. 
that  which  will  be,  the  middle  cannot  possibly  be 
produced  at  one  and  the  same  time.     Moreover  neither  can  the 
interval  §  be  indefinite,  nor  definite,3  since  it  will    §  Between  the 
be  false  to  assert  it  in  the  interval ; 4  but  we  must  past  and  fu- 
consider  what  is  connected  with  it,  so  that  after  the 
having  been  generated,  to  be  generated  may  exist  in  things.5 
Or  is  it  evident  that  what  is  generated  is  not  connected  with 
what  was  generated  ?  for  the  past  does  not  cohere  with  what 
was  generated,  since  they  are  terms  and  individuals.     As  then 
neither  points   are   mutually  connected,  those  things  which 
have  been  produced  are  not  so,  for  both  are  indivisible ;  nor 
for  the  same  reason  does  that  which  is,  cohere  with  that  which 
has  been  generated,  for  that  which  is  generated  is  divisible, 
but  that  which  has  been  is  indivisible.     As  a  line  then  is  to 
a  point,  so  is  that  which  is  to  that  which  was  generated,  for 
infinite  things  which  have  been,  are  inherent  in 
that  which  is  ;||  we  must  however  enunciate  these   poinVin  aline, 
matters  more  clearly  in  the  universal  discussions 
about  motion. % 

Concerning  then  the  manner  in  which,  when 
there  is  a  successive  generation,  the  middle  cause   of  past  and  fu- 

,     .  ,  ,i  ,     <•       .       ,1  i  tures,  some 

subsists,  let  so  much  be  assumed,  tor  in  these  also   principle  or 
it  is  necessary  that  the  middle  and  the  first  should   {j**.*™1184  be 
be  immediate,  thus  A  was  generated  because  C 
was  so,  but  C  was  after,  A  before.     The  principle  indeed  is 


11  Vide  Physics, 
b.  vi. 

5.  In  the  cases 


Vide  Waitz  on  this 


1  As  that  the  house  was  produced. 

2  Supply — with  that  of  which  it  is  the  medium, 
chap.,  vol.  ii.  p.  411 ;  and  CI'.  An.  Prior  ii.  5. 

3  Supply- -in  which  we  may  justly  infer,  that  one  will  be,  because 
another  is. 

*  Since  the  future  does  not  exist  in  that  time. 

4  So  that  there  may  be  a  continual  successive  \  reduction. 


338  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  ii. 

C,  because  it  is  nearer  to  the  now,  which  is  the  principle  of 
time,  but  C  was  generated  if  D  was,  hence  from  D  having 
been,  it  is  necessary  that  A  should  have  been.  The  cause  how- 
ever is  C,  for  from  D  having  been,  it  is  necessary  that  C 
should  have  been  generated,  but  C  having  been,  A  must  of 
necessity  have  been  produced  before.  When  however  we 
thus  assume  the  middle,  will  (the  process)  at  any  time  stop 
at  the  immediate,  or  on  account  of  the  infinity  will  a  medium 
always  intervene  ?  for,  as  we  have  stated,  what  has  been  ge- 
nerated is  not  connected  with  what  has  been  ;  nevertheless  we 
must  commence  at  least  from  the  immediate  *  and 
Mediate,  Tay-     from  the  first  now.1    Likewise  with  regard  to  the 

BekkeUrhle'  ^     "  wil1    be'"  f°r  if   [t  is  trUe  t0  Sa7  that  D  wiU    be> 

it  is  necessary  that,  prior  to  this,  it  should  be  true 
to  say  that  A  will  be,  the  cause  however  of  this  is  C,  for  if  D 
will  be,  prior  to  it  C  will  be,  but  if  C  will  be,  prior  to  it  A 
will  be.  Likewise  also  in  these  the  division  is  infinite,  for 
things  which  will  be,  are  not  mutually  coherent,  but  an  im- 
mediate principle  must  also  be  assumed  in  these.  It  is  thus 
in  the  case  of  works,  if  a  house  has  been  built,  stones  must 
necessarily  have  been  cut,  and  formed  ;  and  why  this  ?  because 
the  foundation  must  of  necessity  have  been  laid,  if  the  house 
was  built,  but  if  the  foundation  was  laid,  stones  must  neces- 
sarily have  been  prepared  before.  Again,  if  there  shall  be  a 
house,  in  like  manner  there  will  be  stones  prior  to  this,  still 
the  demonstration  is  in  like  manner  through  a  medium,  for 
the  foundation  will  have  a  prior  subsistence. 
6.  Things  ge-  Notwithstanding,  since  we  see  in  things  which 
neratedinacir-   are,  that  there  is  a  certain  generation  in  a  circle,! 

clp   must  hjivf  ^^ 

a  similar  de-  this  happens  when  the  middle  and  the  extremes  fol- 
monstratum.  ]ow  each  other,  for  in  these  there  is  a  reciprocation  ; 
ally.  this  however  was  shown  in  the  first  treatise,!  viz. 

ch.  5— 7"  also  that  the  conclusions  are  converted  ;  §  but  the  case 
Post.  An.  b.  i.  0f  being  in  a  circle  is  thus.  In  works  it  appears 
§  changed  into  after  this  manner,  when  the  earth  has  been  moist- 
prem.  ened,  vapour   is  necessarily  produced,  from  the 

production  of  this,  there  is  a  cloud,  from  this  last,  water,  and 
from  the  presence  of  this,  the  earth  is  necessarily  moistened, 
this  however  was  the  (cause)  at  first,  so  that  it  has  come  round 

1  Compare  Waitz  upon  this  place. 


CHAP.  XIII.]  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  339 

in  a  circle,  for  any  one  of  these  existing,  another  is,  :.nd  if 
that  is,  another,  and  from  this,  the  first. 

There  are   some  things  which  are  generated   i.  of  things 
universally,  (for  always,  and  in  every  thing,  they  S^iy,0* 
either  thus  subsist,  or  are  generated,)  but  others   butusuaiiy.the 

,  »         i  ,,  principles 

not  always,  but  for  the  most  part ;  thus  not  every   snouid  be  non- 
vigorous  man  has  a  beard,  but  this  is  generally   f07tjfea£'osbtut 
the  case,  now  of  such  things  it  is  necessary  that   part  true.   cf. 
the  medium  also  should  be  for  the  most  part ;  for   Wallls> IU-  2S> 
if  A  is  universally  predicated  of  B,  and  this  of  C  universally, 
it  is  necessary  that  A  also  should  be  predicated  always,  and 
of  every  C,  (for  the  universal  is  that  which  is  present  with 
every  individual  and  always,)  but  it  was  supposed  to  be  for 
the  most  part,  wherefore  it  is  necessary  that  the  medium  also, 
B,  should  be  for  the  most  part :  hence  of  those  which  are  for 
the  most  part,  the  principles  are  immediate,  as  many  as  thus 
subsist  for  the  most  part,  or  are  generated. 

Chap.  XIII. —  Upon  the  Method  of  investigating  Definition. 

We  have  before  shown  how  what  a  thing  is,  is  attributed  to 
definitions,  and  in  what  way  there  is  or  is  not  a  demonstra- 
tion or  definition  of  it,  how  therefore  it  is  necessary  to  inves- 
tigate1 things  which  are  predicated  in  respect  to  what  a  thing 
is,  let  us  now  discuss. 

Of  those  then,  which  are  always  present  with    i.  Division  of 
each  individual,  some  have  a  wider  extension,  yet   ^tension"3'1 
are  not  beyond  the  genus.*     I  mean  those  have  a   *  of  the  sub- 
wider   extension,    as   many  as  are  present  with   Ject' 
each  individual  universally,  yet  also  with  another  thing,  thus 
there  is   something  which  is  present  with  every  triad,  and 
also  with  that  which  is  not  a  triad,  as  being  is  present  with 
a  triad,  but  also  to  that  which  is  not  number.     Nevertheless 
the  odd  is  present  with  every  triad,  and  is  of  wider  extension, 
for  it  is  with  five,  but  it  is  not  beyond  the  genus,  f 
for  the  five  is  number,  and  nothing  out  of  num- 

i  i     -».t  ii-  ,    j.   i  e         2.  For  the  at 

ber  is  odd.  Now  such  things  we  must  take  so  tar   tainraentofde- 

1  He  uses  the  term  Stiqivuv.  see  also  Mansel's  note  (Appendix  B.)  in 
reference  to  the  expressions  KaTaaicivaZuv  and  Z,r\Ttiv  as  applied  se- 
parately to  the  two  methods  of  "hunting  lor"  *ud  "  testing"  the  defini- 
tion, viz.  Division  and  Induction. 

z  2 


340  ARISTOTLE  S   ORGANON.  [BOOK    II. 

fnition  those  to  until  so  many  are  first  assumed,  each  of  which* 
of  whieh'is  of  is  of  wider  extension,!  but  all  of  them  together 
s1onethaXnebut  are  not  °^  greater  extent,  for  it  is  necessary  that 
an  together  this  should  be  the  substance  of  a  thing.1  For  ex- 
thing  to'be  6de-  ample,  number,  the  odd  is  present  with  every  triad, 
fined  the  first  in  both  ways,  both  as  not  being:  mea- 

*  Taken  separ-  ,    ,  ,  \    '  .     .  °     ,       „ 

ateiy.  sured  by  number  and  as  not  being  composed  of 

t^hingTobe6  numbers.2  Now  therefore  the  triad  is  this,  viz. 
defined.  the  first  odd  number,  and  the  first  in  this  way,  for 

each  of  these  is  present,  the  one  with  all  odd  numbers,  but 
the  last  also  with  the  dual,  yet  all  of  them  (together)  with 
none  (but  the  triad).  Since  however  we  have 
ch^f  b°°k'  shown  above,:}:  that  those  things  which  are  predi- 
cated in  respect  of  what  a  thing  is  are  necessary, 
but  universals  are  necessary,  but  what  are  thus  assumed  of  a 
triangle,  or  any  other  thing,  are  assumed  in  respect  to  what  a 
thing  is,  thus  from  necessity  the  triad  will  be  these  things.  That 
this  however  is  its  essence  appears  from  this,  since  it  is  neces- 
sary, unless  the  very  nature  of  a  triad  were  not  this,  that  this 
should  be  a  certain  genus,  either  denominated  or  anonymous. 
It  will  be  therefore  of  wider  extension  than  to  be  with  a  triad 
alone,  for  let  the  genus  be  supposed  of  that  kind  as  to  be  more 
widely  extended  according  to  power,  if  then  it  is  present  with 
nothing  else  than  individual  triads,  this  will  be  the  essence  of 
the  triad.  Let  this  also  be  supposed,  that  an  ultimate  predi- 
cation like  this  of  individuals  is  the  essence  of  each  thing, 
wherefore  in  like  manner,  when  any  thing  is  thus  demon- 
strated, it  will  be  the  essence  of  that  thing, 
s.  Method  of  Nevertheless  it  is  right  when  any  one  is  con- 

dividing  the  versant  with  a  certain  whole,3  to  divide  the  genus 
i  which  can-     into  the  individuals  which  are  first  in  species,  § 

1  As  some  discrepancy  has  been  supposed  to  exist  between  this  pas- 
sage and  Metap.  vi.  12,  it  may  be  well  to  observe  that,  although  in  the 
latter  passage  he  seems  to  maintain  that  the  last  differentia  must  be  co- 
extensive with  the  subject,  he  is  there  apparently  speaking  not  of  the 
specific  difference  per  se,  but  of  the  difference  regarded  as  dividing  the 
genus :  this  is  in  fact  equivalent  to  saying,  that  the  whole  must  be  co- 
extensive, which  no  one  would  think  of  denying.  Vide  Mansel's  Ap- 
pendix, note  B. ;  Boethius,  Hill,  and  Whately  upon  logical  definition  and 
decision  ;  also  Waitz's  remarks. 

2  Because  the  triad  is  the  first  number,  the  monad  being  the  principle 
of  number,  and  the  dual,  a  medium  between  1  and  3. 

3  In  investigating  the  definition  of  a  subaltern  species. 


CHAP.  Xni."|  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  34 1 

for  instance,  number  into  triad  and  dual,  then  to   not  be  divided 
endeavour  thus  to  assume  the  definitions  of  these,    mt0  sPecles- 
as  of  a  straight  line,  of  a  circle,1  and  of  a  right  angle  ;  after- 
wards assuming  what  the  genus  is,2  for  instance,  whether  it 
is  quantity  or  quality,  he  should  investigate  the  peculiar  pas- 
sions* through  common  first  (principles.)3     For   *of  the  first 
those  which  happen  to  the  composites  from  indi-   species, 
viduals  will  be  evident  from  the  definitions,!  be-   t  of  the  first 
cause  definition   and  that  which  is  simple4  are   sPecies- 
the  principles  of  all  things,  and  accidents  are  essentially  pre- 
sent with  simple  things  alone,  but  with  others  according  to 
them.     The  divisions  indeed  by  differences5  are   4  Differential 
useful  for  our  progression  in  this  way,  but  how   division  useful 
indeed  they  demonstrate  we  have  shown  before,^   gation  of  den-' 
but   they  would  thus  be  useful  only  for  syllo-   "u!on-    . 

1  .1    •  •  T       •        1  1      V  I    An'    Prl0r  '■ 

gizing  what  a  thing  is,  and  indeed  they  may  ap-   ch.3i,and  tiiia 
pear  to  do  nothing,  but  to  assume  every  thing   ^    '      5" 
immediately,§  just  as  if  any  one  assumed  from    H-e.  without 
the  beginning  without  division.     It  makes  some 
difference,  however,  whether  what  is  predicated  be  so,  prior  or 
posterior,6  as  for  instance,  whether  we  call  animal,  mild  biped, 
or  biped,  animal  mild,  for  if  every  thing  consists 
of  two,||  and  one  certain   thing  is  animal  mild,    a;ffeerenceand 
and  again  from  this,  and  the  difference,  man  or 
any  thing  else  which  is  one,  consists,   we  must  necessarily 
make  a  postulate  by  division.    Besides,  thus  only  is  it  possible 
to  leave  out  nothing  in  the  definition,  since  when  the  first 
genus  is  assumed,  if  a  person  takes  a  certain  inferior  division,7 
every  thing  will  not  fall  into  this  ;   for  instance,  not  every 
animal  has  entire  or  divided  wings,  but  every  animal  which 
is  winged,  for  this  is  the  difference  of  it,1f  but  the    'i-e.  thedivi- 
first  difference  of  animal  is  that  into  which  every   Taylor. 

1  A  circle  is  first  amongst  figures,  because  it  is  circumscribed  by  one 
line,  other  figures  by  many  lines. 

2  In  what  category  the  thing  defined  is  contained. 

3  Principles  common  to  the  first  .and  remaining  lowest  species,  for  the 
principles  of  the  subaltern  are  those  of  the  infinia  species. 

*  The  defin.  of  the  first  simple  species.  &  Specific  differences. 

•  Therefore  division  is  useful  for  the  arrangement  of  things  properly 
in  regard  to  priority,  etc.  Cf.  Waitz. 

7  In  winch  there  is  not  the  peculiarity  of  genus,  but  of  some  lowet 
species. 


342 


ARISTOTLE  S    ORGANON. 


[lJOOK    II. 


animal  falls.     Likewise  in  regard  to  each  of  the  rest,  both  of 
*  The  first  di-     those  genera  *  which  are  external  to  animal,  and 

vision  is  to  be 
assumed, 
t  The  first  di- 
vision of  bird. 


I  In  the  defini 
tion. 

5.  It  is  not  re- 
quisite that  he 
who  defines 
should  know 
all  other  sub- 
jects from 
which  he  dis- 
tinguishes the 
tiling  defined. 


of  those  which  are  contained  under  it,  as  of  bird,f 
is  that  into  which  every  bird  falls,  and  of  fish 
that  into  which  every  fish  falls.  Thus  proceeding 
we  may  know  that  nothing  is  omitted,  J  but  other- 
wise we  must  omit  something,  and  not  know  it. 
It  is  not  at  all  necessary  that  he  who  defines  and 
divides,  should  know  all  things  that  subsist,1 
though  some  say  it  is  impossible  to  know  the  dif- 
ferences of  each  thing  without  knowing  each  ; 
but  it  is  impossible  to  know  each  thing  without 
differences,  for  that  from  which  this  does  not  dif- 
fer, is  the  same  with  this,  but  that  from  which  it  differs  is 
something  else  than  this.  In  the  first  place  then  this  is  false,  for 
it  is  not  something  else  according  to  every  difference,  since,  there 
are  many  differences  in  things  which  are  the  same  in  species,  yet 
not  according  to  substance,  nor  per  se.  Next,  when  any  one 
fi.  a  division  assumes  opposites,  and  difference,  and  that  every 
thing  falls  into  this  or  that,  and  assumes  also  that 
the  question  is  in  one  part  of  the  two,  and  knows 
this,  it  is  of  no  consequence  whether  he  knows 
or  does  not  those  other  things  of  which  the  dif- 
ferences §  are  predicated.  For  it  is  evident  that 
thus  proceeding, j|  if  he  should  arrive  at  those  of 
which  there  is  no  longer  a  difference,  he  will  ob- 
tain the  definition  of  the  substance  ;  but  that  every  thing  will 
fall  into  division,  if  there  should  be  opposites  of  which  there 
is  no  medium,  is  not  a  postulate,^  since  every 
thing  must  necessarily  be  in  one  of  them,  if  in- 
deed it  will  be  the  difference  of  it. 

In  order  to  frame  definition  by  divisions,  we 
must  attend  to  three  things,  viz.  to  assume  the 
things  predicated  in  respect  of  what  a  thing 
is ;  to  arrange  these,  which  shall  be  first  or  se- 
cond ;  and  that  these  are  all.     Now  the  first  of 


into  opposite 
members,  as  of 
animal  into 
rational  and 
irrational. 


§  Rational, etc. 

II  From  genus 
to  species  by 
differences. 


5  Not  a  petitio 
principii. 


7.  Three  things 
to  be  attended 
to,  in  division- 
al definition — 
how  to  effect 
these.     Vide 
Whately,  Kill, 
and  Aldrich. 


1  We  find  from  the  scholia  that  Aristotle  here  glances  at  Speusippus :  he 
proceeds  to  show  that  it  does  not  signify  tc  the  proper  knowledge  of  the 
thing  defined,  whether  a  person  knows,  or  does  not  know,  other  things  in- 
cluded in  either  species ;  since  if  he  carries  on  division  he  will  arrive  at  those 
which  have  no  difference,  and  will  then  have  attained  the  desired  definition. 


CHAP.  Xni.f  TIIE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  343 

these  arises  from  our  being  able  as  syllogistically   '  y.         . 
to  collect  accident,  that  it  is  inherent,*  so  to  con-   took  a.      '  ' 
struct  through  genus.f    There  will  however  be  a    t  Topics,  book 
proper  arrangement  if  what  is  first  be  assumed,   1V' 
and  this  will  be  if  that  be  taken  which  is  consequent  to  all, 
but  all  not  consequent  to  it ;  for  there  must  be  something  of 
this  kind.     This  then  being  taken,  there  must  now  be  the 
same  method  in  the  things  inferior,  since  the  second  will  be 
that  which  is  first  of  the  rest,  and  the  third  that  which  is  first 
of  the  following,  for  what  is  superior  being  taken  away,  what- 
ever succeeds  will  be  the  first  of  the  others ;   there  is  also 
similar  reasoning  in  the  other  cases.    Still  that  all  these  should 
be,  is  clear  from  assuming  what  is  first  in  the  division,  that 
every  animal  is  either  this  or  that,|  but  this  is   *  e      ratj0nai 
inherent ;  §  and  again  the  difference  of  this  whole  '    or  irrational, 
but  that  of  the  last 2  there  is  no  longer  any  differ-      e" g" ra  lona  ' 
ence,  or  immediately  with  the  last  difference  3  this  ||    n  Being  as- 
does  not  differ  in  species  from  the  whole:4  for  it   sumed- 
is  clear  that  neither  more  (than  is  necessary)  is  added,  for  every 
thing  has  been  assumed  in  reference  to  what  a   8  The  gum. 
thing  is,  nor  is  any  thing  deficient,  for  it  would  mum  genus 
be  either  genus  or  difference.    Both  the  first  then   definition. 
is  genus,  and  this  assumed  together  with  differ-   J  Essential. 

0  *  o  *  Aninia.1   ra- 

ences,  but  all  the  differences  are  contained,  for  tionai,  mortal, 
there  is  no  longer  any  posterior  difference.^"  +laE*s'entiaiiy 
Otherwise  the  last*  would  differ  in  species,  this   from  the  whole 

,  ,         ,  ,  vfl.       1  animal,  ration- 

however  has  been  shown  not  to  dmer.j  ai,  mortai. 

Still  we  must  investigate,  looking  to  those  which       Metnod  t0 
are  similar  and  do  not  differ,  first  (considering)  what   be  applied  in 
that  is  which  is  the  same  in  all  these,  then  again   veral^pedeT 
in  other  things  which  are  in  the  same  genus  with   with  some- 

,  ,       ,  .   ,  .-,  ,  ,-,  thingcommon. 

them,  and  which  are  among  themselves  the  same 

in  species,  but  different  from  those.    Yet  when  in  these  that  is 

1  Subdivision  of  rational  animal  into  mortal,  immortal,  etc. 

2  As  of  mortal  rational  animal. 

3  This  may  be  some  accidental  difference,  e.  g.  "  black,"  united  to  the 
last,  as  animal  rational  mortal  black. 

*  That  is,  from  animal  rational  mortal,  but  as  it  does  not  differ  from  it 
essentially,  the  last  accidental  difference  (black)  ought  not  to  be  admit- 
ted. He  uses  the  term  to  trvvoXov,  when  the  definition  is  composed  of 
the  genua  and  its  differences.  Of.  Wait/.,  Boethius,  and  Keckermann'8 
Lyst.  Log.    Mm.  lib.  i.  cap.  17.    Wallis,  Log. 


344  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  ii. 

assumed  which  all  have  the  same,  and  in  others  similarly,  we 
must  consider  in  the  things  assumed  whether  it  is  the  same, 
until  we  arrive  at  one  reason,  for  this  will  be  the  definition  of 
the  thing.  Yet  if  we  do  not  arrive  at  one,  but  at  two  or 
more,  it  is  evident  that  the  question  will  not  be  one,  but 
*  ue-raXoiWa.  many>  f°r  instance,  I  mean  if  we  should  inquire 
cf.  Eth.  Nic.      what  magnanimity  *  is,  we  must  consider  in  the 

iv.  3  and  4,  and  n  .    •  •  i 

shaks.  corioia-  cases  ot  certain  magnanimous  persons,  whom  we 
nus,  passim.  know  what  one  thing  they  all  possess,  so  far  as 
they  are  such.  Thus  if  Alcibiades  is  magnanimous,  or 
Achilles,  or  Ajax,  what  one  thing  have  they  all?  intolerance 

t  Alcibiades  °^  msultj  f°r  one  °f  them  fought,1  f  another 
sulked,2  another  slew  himself.:):  Again,  in  other 
instances,  as  in  that  of  Lysander  or  Socrates.  If 
then  (it  is  common  to  these)  to  behave  in  the  same  manner, 
in  prosperity  and  adversity,  taking  these  two,  I  consider  what 
indifference  with  regard  to  fortune,  and  what  impatience  under 
insult  possess  in  common  ;  if  they  have  nothing  there  will  be 
two  species  of  magnanimity. 

Every  definition  is  nevertheless  universal,  for 
daily  universal  the  physician  does  not  prescribe  what  is  whole- 
to°be  defined  some  f°r  a  certain  eye,  but  defines  what  is  fit  for 
every  eye,  or  for  the  species.  The  singular  however 
is  easier  to  define  than  the  universal,  wherefore  we  must  pass 
from  singulars  to  universals,  for  equivocations  lie  more  con- 
cealed in  universals,  than  in  things  without  a  difference.  But 
as  in  demonstrations  the  power  of  syllogizing  must  necessarily 
«  videi  •  i  ^e  inherent,  so  also  perspicuity  must  be  in  de- 
ruies  for  defini-  finitions,§  and  there  will  be  this,  if  through  things 
tion  m  Aidncn.  wj1jc}1  are  singularly  enunciated,  what  is  in  each 
genus  be  separately  defined ;  as  with  the  similar,  not  every 
similar,  but  that  which  is  in  colours  and  in  figures,  and  the 

1  Alcibiades,  to  revenge  the  preference  given  by  his  countrymen  to 
Lysias,  revolted  to  Lacedeemon,  and  brought  war  on  his  country. 

2  Achilles,  for  Briseis.  The  reader  may  smile  at  the  graphic  term 
used  here  for  s/xijvio-tv,  as  descriptive  of  the  "angry  boy"  in  the  Iliad, 
but  will  confess  that  its  use  is  warranted,  both  verbally,  by  Johnson, 
and  circumstantially,  by  Shakspeare  (Troilus  and  Cressida).  Upon  the 
freaks  and  follies  of  Ajax,  see  the  speech  of  Thersites  in  the  same  play, 
act  iii.  scene  3,  and  Sophocles  (Ajax)  passim.  Zell  observes  that  mag- 
nanimity was  a  conspicuous  element  in  Aristotle's  own  character:  upon 
Christian  magnanimity,  see  St.  Paul's  Epistles. 


CHAP.  XIV.l  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  345 

sharp  that  which  is  in  voice,  and  so  to  proceed  to  what  is 
common,  taking  care  that  equivocation  does  not   «  Because  of 
occur.     But  if  it  is  not  right  to  use  metaphors  in   l^f^edefi- 
disputation,  we  must  clearly  not  define  by  meta-   nition  is  some- 
phors,*  nor  by  those  things  which  are  spoken  by   JftJ  l™^0/.' 
metaphor,  otherwise  it  will  be  necessary  to  use   sion.   (cf 

r.  .       ,.  ,  Waitz,  vol.  il. 

metaphors  in  disputation,  j  P.  420 ) 

Chap.  XIV.— Rules  for  Problems*  t  Cf.  An.  Prior 

J  T  1.  4,  and  1.  2G  ; 

also  Topics  i.  4, 

Now  that  we  may  have  problems,  we  must  select   and  i.  11. 
sections  and  divisions,  and  thus  select,  the  com-    \  Needofdiyi- 

_     ,.         .    '  ,  c  ,         sion  for  rightly 

mon  genus  of  all  being  supposed,  as  lor  example,   appropriating 
if  animals  were  the  subjects  of  consideration,  (we   ^h'sdeVce. 
must  first  consider,)  what  kind  of  things  are  pre- 
sent with  every  animal.1     When  these  have  been  taken,  we 
must  again  see  what  kind  of  things  are  consequent  to  every 
first  individual  of  the  rest,2  thus  if  this  is  a  bird,  what  things 
follow  every  bird,  and  so  always  that  which  is  nearest,3  for 
we  shall  evidently  now  be  able  to  say  why  things  are  present, 
which  are  consequent  to  those  under  what  is  common,  as  why 
they  are  present  with  man  or  horse.4     Let  then  animal  be  A, 
B  things  consequent  to  every  animal,  C  D  E  certain  animals, 
why  then  B  is  present  with  D  is  evident,  for  it  is  present 
through  A :  in  a  similar  manner  with  the  rest,  and 

„*=,.,  ,  •         c  §  Example  (1.) 

in  others  there  is  always  the  same  reasoning.  § 

1  For  the  word  problem  and  its  uses,  see  Alexander  Scholia,  p.  150, 
b.  40.  What  he  means  here,  is  that  we  ascertain  the  questions  or  pro- 
blems to  be  discussed  in  every  system,  by  the  use  of  proper  divisions  and 
sections,  (which  Aristotle  assumes  l'or  the  same  thing,)  and  by  proceed- 
ing from  universals  to  singulars.    Vide  Biese  i.  p.  314. 

2  Of  the  first  species. 

3  To  the  first  species,  which  is  next  to  the  proposed  genus.    Taylor. 

4  i.  e.  the  properties  of  animal. 

A  B 

Ex.  1.  Every  animal  is  sentient 
D  A 

Every  horse  is  an  animal 
D  B 

.  • .  Every  horse  is  sentient. 
The  proof  may  be   applied  in  the  same  manner  to   every  species     f 
animal. 


346 


Aristotle's  organon. 


[book  II. 


Now  then  we  speak  according  to  presented 
common  names,1*  but  we  must  not  only  consider 
in  these,  but  also  assume  if  any  thing  else  should 
be  seen  to  be  common,  afterwards  consider  to 
what  things  this  is  consequent,  and  the  quality  of 
the  things  consequent  to  this,2  as  those  consequent 
to  having  horns  are  the  possession  of  a  rough  muscular  lining 
to  the  stomach,  and  the  not  having  teeth  in  both  jaws. 
Moreover  to  what  things  the  possession  of  horns 
is  consequent,  for  it  will  be  evident  why  what 
has  been  mentioned  f  is  present  with  them,  J  for 
it  will  be  so  in  consequence  of  their  possessing 
horns. 

There  is  yet  another  mode  of  selection  by  anal- 
ogy^ since  it  is  impossible  to  assume  one  and  the 
same  thing,  which  it  is  necessary  to  call  sepium, 
spine,  and  bone,  there  are  also  things  consequent 
to  these,  as  if  there  were  one  certain  nature  of 
this  kind.3 


*  Synonyms. 
2.  Also  of  in- 
vestigating 
that  which  is 
inherent  in  the 
singulars  as 
something 
common. 


t  Viz.  to  have 
teeth  in  one 
jaw  only,  etc. 
J  With  the  spe- 
cies of  horned 
animals. 

3.  Selection 
jcaTu  to  ava~ 
\oyov. 
§  i.  e.  to  as- 
sume a  com- 
mon analogous 
thing. 


Chap.  XV. — Of  Identical  Problems. 

l.  Problems  are  Some  problems  are  the  same  from  having  the  same 
haTeeithM'tne  medium,  f°r  instance,  because  all  things  are  an 
same  middle      antiperistasis,4  but  of  these  some  are  the  same  in 

1  Cf.  Top.  i.  5;  Categ.  ch.  1.  Synonyms  are  not  allowed  to  be  real 
definitions,  in  the  proper  sense,  by  Aristotle,  though  admitted  to  be 
optica  ;  as  nominal  definitions,  they  are  recognised  by  Alexander  on 
Metaph.  vi.  4,  p.  442,  Bonitz  ed.,  but  the  genuineness  of  this  portion  of 
the  commentary  has  been  questioned.  Vide  Mansel's  Logic  on  Definition. 

2  We  must  not  only  use  this  method  in  things  synonymous,  and  in- 
vestigate the  common  generic  properties,  and  afterwards  the  specific  pecu- 
liarities, but  if  there  be  any  thing  common  without  a  name,  yet  we  must 
assume  it,  in  order  to  investigate  its  properties,  and  afterwards  to  con- 
sider to  what  species  it  is  attributed,  and  the  quality  of  the  things  which 
are  consequent  to  the  anonymous  genus. 

3  The  instances  given  are  analogous,  because  there  is  the  same  relation 
of  the  sepium  in  a  particular  kind  of  fish ;  of  the  spine  in  fish  gener- 
ally, and  of  bone  in  quadrupeds.  He  means  that  from  a  certain  analogy, 
which  is  expressive  of  some  common  nature  in  things,  we  may  ascertain 
what  is  common  to  various  individuals.    Cf.  Scholia,  p.  42,  a.  37,  47. 

4  Quod  omnia  fiant  quia  contraria  qualitas  cerminus  instat.  Buhle. 
Compressio  undique  circumfusa.    Scap.  Theoph.  de  Caus.  pi.  1,  2.     The 


CHAP.  XVI. 1  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  347 

genus,  which  have  differences  from  belonging  to  term,  ore/ 
other  things,  or  from  subsisting  differently,  e.  g.  *s  subjected"^ 
why  is  there  an  echo,  or  why  is  there  a  reflection,  the  oper- 
and why  a  rainbow  ?  for  all  these  are  the  same  problem  in 
genus,  (for  all  are  reflection,)  but  they  differ  in  species.1 
Other  problems  differ  from  the  medium  being  contained  under 
another  medium,  as  why  does  the  Nile  have  a  greater  flow 
during  the  fall  of  the  month  ?  2  because  the  fall  of  the  month 
is  more  winterly  :  but  why  is  the  fall  more  winterly  ?  because 
the  moon  fails,  for  thus  do  these  subsist  towards  each  other. 

Chap.  XVI.—  Of  Causes  and  Effects. 

Some  one  may  perhaps  doubt  concerning  cause  difficuUy— the* 
and  that  of  which  it  is  the  cause,  whether  when  middle  tenn 
the  effect  is  inherent,  the  cause  also  is  inherent,  ^pres/the^ 
as  if  the  leaves  fall  from  a  tree,  or  there  is  an  cause  of  the  in- 
eclipse,  will  there  also  be  the  cause  of  the  eclipse,  Aidrich's  Lor., 
or  of  the  fall  of  the  leaves  ?  As  if  the  cause  of  Jj^^Sg 
this,  is  the  having  broad  leaves,  but  of  an  eclipse  Log.) 
the  interposition  of  the  earth,  for  if  this  be  not  so,  something 
else  will  be  the  cause  of  these,  and  if  the  cause  is  present,  at 
the  same  time  the  effect  will  be,  thus  if  the  earth  be  interposed, 
there  is  an  eclipse,  or  if  a  tree  have  broad  leaves,  it  sheds 
them.  But  if  this  be  so,  they  would  be  simultaneous,  and  de- 
monstrated through  each  other,  for  let  the  leaves  to  fall  be  A, 
the  having  broad  leaves  B,  and  a  vine  C,  if  then  A  is  present 
with  B,  (for  whatever  has  broad  leaves  sheds  them,)  but  B  is 
present  with  C,  for  every  vine  has  broad  leaves,  A  is  present 
with  C,  and  every  vine  sheds  its  leaves,  but  the  cause  is  B, 

word  signifies  the  effect  produced  from  a  thing  being  surrounded  by  its 
contrary.  Thus  why  is  hail  produced  ?  Because  the  cold  is  contracted  by 
the  surrounding  heat.  Why  are  subterranean  places  cold  in  summer  and 
hot  in  winter  ?  Because  in  winter  the  heat  is  contracted  on  account  of 
the  surrounding  cold,  and  in  summer  the  cold,  on  account  of  the  sur- 
rounding heat.    Taylor.     Cf.  Physic,  b.  iv.  v.  vi. ;  also  Lucretius. 

1  Reflection  of  the  air  produces  the  echo ;  of  the  figure  in  the  mirror 
produces  the  image ;  of  the  sun's  rays  produces  the  rainbow. 

*  During  the  fall  of  the  month  there  is  more  rain  ;  hence  the  Nile  rises, 
and  there  is  more  rain  during  the  decrease  of  the  moon,  because  -when 
her  light  fails,  she  more  powerfully  excites  humid  bodies.  Taylor.  Ci. 
also  Herod,  lib.  ii.  c.  19 — 25. 


348  Aristotle's  org  axon.  [book  it. 

•  ei  m  ^ie  middle.*  We  may  also  show  that  the  vine 
has  broad  leaves,  from  its  shedding  them,  for  if 
D  be  what  has  broad  leaves,  E  to  shed  the  leaf,  F  a  vine,  E 
then  is  present  with  F,  (for  every  vine  sheds  its  leaf,)  but  D 
with  E,  (for  every  thing  which  sheds  its  leaf,  has  broad 
leaves,)  every  vine  then  has  broad  leaves,  the  cause  is,  its 
.  shedding  them,  j*  Nevertheless  if  they  cannot  be 
the  cause  of  each  other,  (since  cause  is  prior  to 
that  of  which  it  is  the  cause,)  the  cause  of  an  eclipse  indeed 
is  the  interposition  of  the  earth,  but  an  eclipse  is  not  the 
cause  of  the  earth  interposing.  If  then  the  demonstration  by 
cause  (shows)  why  a  thing  is,  but  that  which  is  not  through 
cause,  that  it  is,  one  knows1  indeed  that  the  earth  is  inter- 
posed, but  why  it  is,  he  does  not  know.2  Yet  that  an 
eclipse  is  not  the  cause  of  the  interposition,  but  this  of  an 
eclipse,  is  plain,  since  in  the  definition  of  an  eclipse,  the  in- 
terposition of  the  earth  is  inherent,  so  that  evidently  that  is 
known  through  this,3  but  not  this  through  that.4 

2  There  is  ^*r  may  tnere  be  many  causes  of  one  thing  ? 

only  one  cause  for  if  the  same  tiling  may  be  predicated  of  many 
slmeethi"ids>the  primary,  let  A  be  present  with  B  a  first,  and 
from  which  it  with  C  another  first,  and  these  with  D  E,  A  then 
will  be  present  with  D  E,  but  the  cause  why  it  is 
with  D  will  be  B,  and  C  the  cause  why  it  is  with  E,  hence 
from  the  existence  of  the  cause  there  is  necessarily  the  ex- 

B  A 

Ex.  1.  Whatever  consists  of  broad  leaves  sheds  its  leaves 
C  B 

Every  vine  consists  of  broad  leaves 
C  A 

. ' .  Every  vine  sheds  its  leaves. 

E  D 

Ex.  2.  Whatever  sheds  its  leaves  has  broad  leaves 
F  E 

Every  vine  sheds  its  leaves 
F  D 

.  • .  Every  vine  has  broad  leaves. 

1  i.  e.  he  who  through  an  eclipse  proves  the  interposition  of  the  earth. 

2  That  is,  one  kind  of  knowledge  (that  of  the  on)  is  empirical,  but  the 
other  (that  of  the  Siori)  is  scientific.     Cf.  Ethic.  Nic.  b.  i.  c.  5. 

*  The  eclipse  is  proved  through  the  interposition  of  the  earth. 

*  Cause  is  not  truly  proved  through  effect,  because  the  true  demonstra- 
tion is  of  the  "  why,"  but.  demonstration  from  effect  is  of  the  "  that." 


CHAP.  XVII.]  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  349 

istence  of  the  thing,  but  when  the  thing  exists,  it  is  not  ne- 
cessary that  every  cause  should  exist,  still  some  cause  indeed, 
yet  not  every  cause.  Or  if  the  problem  is  always  universal, 
is  the  cause  also  a  certain  whole,  and  that  of  which  it  is  the 
cause  universal  ? '  as  to  shed  the  leaf  is  present  definitely  with 
a  certain  whole,*  though  there  should  be  species 

°.  ii-  »  i_  •  i_         ^r  genus. 

of  it,2  and  with  these  universally,  1.  e.  either  with 
plants  or  with  such  plants.f    Hence  in  these,  the    t  e_  g  plants 
medium  and  that  of  which  it  is  the  cause  must   with  broad 
be  equal,  and  reciprocate,3  for  instance,  why  do 
the   trees  shed  their  leaves?  if  indeed  through  the  concre- 
tion of  moisture,  whether  the  tree  casts  its  leaf,  there  must 
of  necessity  be  concretion,  or  whether  there  is  concretion  not 
in  any  thing  indiscriminately,  but  in  a  tree,  the  latter  must 
necessarily  shed  its  leaf. 

Chap.  XVII.  —Extension  of  the  same  subject. 

Whether  however  may  there  not  be  possibly  the  i.  If  the  same 

same  cause  of  the  same  thing4  in  all  things,5  but  ^ESSf™* 

a  different  one,  or  is  this  impossible?  or  shall  we  except  there  is 

say  it  cannot  happen,  if  it  is  demonstrated  per  se  deinMiftratfon, 

and  not  by  a  sign  or  accident?6  for  the  middle  is  it  must  be 

the  definition  of  the  extreme,7  but  if  it  is  not  thus,  thesame cause. 

(shall  we  say  that)  it  is  possible?8     We  may  g^gg^. 

however  consider  that  of  which9  and  to  which10  cai,  the  middle 

1  "  Universal "  is  here  used  in  the  same  sense  as  in  ch.  iv.  of  the  pre- 
ceding book,  when  a  property  is  predicated  of  every  subject  and  prima- 
rily, so  as  to  reciprocate  with  it.     Cf.  Waitz,  vol.  ii.  424. 

2  The  property  may  be  in  the  several  species  as  in  the  genus,  but  its 
presence  in  the  latter  does  not  prevent  its  predication  of  the  former. 

3  Reciprocals  are  called  equals  because  they  are  identical  in  quantity. 

4  Property — which  in  the  demonstration  is  the  major  extreme. 

s  In  subjects  which  are  the  minor  extremes— by  cause  understand,  the 
middle  term. 
•  Cf.  Anal.  Pr.  ch.  xxvii.  and  Waitz,  p.  425,  vol.  ii. 

7  Of  the  major,  see  below. 

8  That  if  it  is  not  demonstrated  per  se,  but  from  accident,  there  may 
be  many  causes. 

8  The  property. 

10  The  subject,  it  is  possible  to  consider  these  from  accident,  just  as  if 
a  grammarian  was  proved  visible,  because  man  is  visible.     Taylor. 


350  Aristotle's  okganon.  [book  ii. 

term  wm  be  jt  [s  t]ie  cause  foy  accident,  still  they  do  not  ap- 
Post.  i.  13.  pear  to  be  problems,1  but  if  not,  the  medium  will 
subsist  similarly,2  if  indeed  they  are  equivocal,  the  medium 
will  be  equivocal,  if  however  as  in  genus3  the  medium  will 
be  similar.  For  instance,  why  is  there  alternate  proportion  ? 
for  there  is  a  different  cause  in  lines,  and  in  numbers,  and 

the  same  (medium)  so  far  as  they  are  lines,  is  differ- 
samemedium  ent,*  but  so  far  as  it  has  an  increase  of  the  same 
quoad  num-  kind,f  it  is  the  same,  the  like  also  occurs  in  all 
t  Muitipiica-  things.  There  is  indeed  a  different  cause  in  a 
ciid'bookv.Eu*   different  subject,  why  colour  is  similar  to  colour, 

and  figure  to  figure,  for  the  similar  in  these  is 
.  T   .  equivocal,  for  heret   perhaps  it  is  to  have  the 

I  In  figures.  .*  '  +    i  f 

sides  analogous,  and  the  angles  equal,  but  in  co- 
lours it  consists  in  there  being  one  sense  (of  their  perception) 
or  something  else  of  the  kind.  Things  however  analogically 
the  same,  will  have  also  the  same  medium  by  analogy,  and  this 
.  i  e  the  mid-  ^s  so  fr°m  cause,  §  and  that  of  which,  ||  and  to 
die.  which  %  it  is  the  cause  following  each  other  ;  but 

extreme.aJ°r  by  assuming  each  singly,*  that  of  which  it  is  the 
it  The  minor      cause  is  more  widely  extended,  as  for  the  exter- 

extreme* 

*  The  several  nal  angles  to  be  equal  to  four,  is  of  wider  exten- 
nimorS  °f  the  S10n  t'ian  triangle  or  square,  but  equal  f  in  all,  for 
t  with  the  ge-  whatever  have  external  angles  equal  to  four  right, 
"eTheyUrecT-  will  also  have  the  medium  similarly. J  The  me- 
procate.  dium  however  is  the  definition  of  the  first  ex- 

treme,4 wherefore  all  sciences  are  produced  by  definition,  thus 
§  Magis  com-     t°  shed  the  leaf,  is  at  the  same  time  consequent  to 
mune  est.         the  vine,  and  exceeds,  §5  and  to  the  fig  tree,  and 
exceeds,  yet  does  not  exceed  all  (plants),  but  is 

1  Because  problems  ought  to  be  ''per  se,"  not  from  accident. 

2  To  the  extremes.  3  They  are  synonymous. 

4  Vide  Mansel,  Appendices  B.  and  H.,  and  cf.  upon  the  method  of  in- 
terpretation to  be  used  here,  Anal.  Post.  i.  4,  and  i.  5.  Aristotle  intends 
by  the  middle  being  the  definition  of  the  major  extreme,  that  it  is  so  of 
the  property  which  is  demonstrated.  For  instance,  why  does  it  thunder  ? 
or  why  is  there  a  noise  in  a  cloud  ?  because  fire  is  extinguished.  What 
is  thunder?  An  extinction  of  fire  in  a  cloud  :  here  the  medium  is  the 
definition  of  the  major  extreme,  thunder,  and  not  of  the  less,  that  is,  of  a 
cloud. 

5  Vide  Waitz,  vol.  ii.  p.  426-7,  and  the  Port  Royal  Logic,  p.  i.  ch.  vi., 
also  Mansel,  App.  A. 


C:iAP.  XVII.]  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS.  3.51 

equal  to  them.    If  then  you  take  the  first  middle1  2.  The  major 
it  is  the  definition  of  shedding  the  leaf,  for  the  (S°tj**£ 
first  will  be  the  middle  of  one  of  them,  because  nor  in  extent, 
all  are  such,2  next  the  middle  of  this*  is,  that  sap  oughT  to  ex- 
is  congealed,  or  something  else  of  the  sort,  but  c?^d  l,he  indi" 

o  '  °  viduals  com- 

what  is  it  to  shed  the  leaf  ?  it  is  for  the  sap  to  be   prehended. 
congealed,  at  the  junction  of  the  seed.  of  ^pianfhav- 

In  figures,  to  those  who  investigate  the  conse-   inR  broa(i 

^  leaves 

quence  of  the  cause,  and  of  what  it  is  the  cause, 
we  may  explain  the  matter  thus :  let  A  be  present  with  every 
B,  and  B  with  every  D,  but  more  extensively,  B  then  will 
be  universal  to  D,  I  call  that  universal  which      _ 

,  .  .   ,  ,  ,       .,  .  .      t  Cum  latius 

does  not  reciprocate,  y  but  that  the  first  universal,  sit.  Buhie. 

with  which  each  singular  does  not  reciprocate,  fs' p/edlcated'of 

but  all  together  reciprocate,  and  are  of  similar  ex-  things  differing 

tension.     B  then  is  the  cause  why  A  is  present  canb^demon- 

with  D,  wherefore  it  is  necessary  that  A  should  seated  by  di- 

verse  roiclul& 

be  more  widely  extended  than  B,  for  if  not,  why   terms. 
will  this  J  be   rather  the  cause  than  that?§     If  jB 
then  A  is  present  with  all  those  of  E,  all  those   §  a. 
will  be  some  one  thing  different  from  B,||  for  if 
not,  how  will  it  be  possible  to  say  that  A  is   present  with 
every  thing  with  which  E  is,  but  E  not  with  every  thing 
with  which  A  is  ?  for  why  will  there  not  be  a  certain  cause 
as  there  is  why  A  is  present  with  all  D  ?    wherefore  will  all 
those  of  E  be  one  thing  ?     We  must  consider  this,  and  let 

1  The  first  universal  subject  in  which  the  property  is  inherent — e.  g. 
a  plant  with  broad  leaves,  in  which  the  falling  oft'  of  leaves  is  present. 

2  i.  e.  The  universal  subject  will  be  the  cause  of  the  leaves  falling,  as 
to  the  vine,  fig  tree,  &c.  because  all  vines  and  fig  trees  are  plants  with 
broad  leaves.  Vide  Biese  i.  p.  317. 

B  A 

Ex.  1.  Whatever  is  without  bile  is  long-lived 
D  B 

Every  quadruped  is  without  bile 
D  A 

'  .  Every  quadruped  is  long-lived. 

C  A 

Every  animal  of  a  dry  complexion  is  long-lived 

E  C 

Every  bird  is  an  animal  of  a  dry  complexion 
E  A 

.  • .  Evert  bird  is  long-lived. 


352 


ARISTOTLE  S   ORGANON. 


[book  IT. 


»  As  B  and  C. 

t  Of  the  same 
property  as  of 
A. 

I  D  and  E  dif- 
fer in  species. 

§  i.  e.  an  inde- 
monstrable 
proposition. 
||  Example  (1.) 
IT  Each  under 
the  other. 


there  be  C,  hence  there  may  be  many  causes* 
of  the  same  thing,  f  but  not  to  the  same  in  spe- 
cies,! for  instance,  the  cause  why  quadrupeds 
are  long-lived,  is  their  not  having  bile,  but  why 
birds  live  long,  their  being  of  a  dry  complexion, 
or  something  else  :  if  however  they  do  not  arrive 
immediately  at  an  individual, §  and  there  is  not 
one  medium  only,  but  many,  ||  the  causes  also  are 
many.^f 


Chap.  XVIII. —  Observation  upon  Cause  to  Singulars. 


»  As  to  D. 
1.  The  middle 
term  ought  to 
be  the  nearest 
to  the  singular 
to  which  it  is 
cause, 
t  As  B. 
I  A. 
S  In  D. 

||  Example  (1.) 


Which  of  the  media  is  the  cause  to  singulars,* 
whether  that  which  belongs  to  the  first  universal, 
or  that  to  the  singular  ?  Evidently  the  nearest 
to  the  singular  to  which  it  is  cause.1  For  this  is 
the  cause  why  the  first, j"  under  the  universal,^  is 
inherent,^  C  is  the  cause  that  B  is  inherent  in 
D,  hence  C  is  the  cause  why  A  is  inherent  in  D, 
but  B  is  the  cause  why  it  is  in  C,  yet  to  this  it- 
self is  the  cause.2  II 


Chap.  XIX. —  Upon  the  Method  and  Habit  necessary  to  the  ascer- 
tainment of  Principles. 

Concerning  syllogism  then  and  demonstration,  what  either 
of  them  is,  and  how  it  is  produced,  is  clear,  and  at  the  same 
f  Taylor  and  time  a°out  demonstrative  science,  for  it  is  the 
Buhie  ar.-nex      same  :  %  3  but  about  principles,  how  they  become 

1  The  medium  is  to  be  assumed,  proximate  to  the  subject  rather  than 
to  the  property.  Habet  et  Aid™  suos  gradus,  quia  potest  esse  causa 
proxima  quae  non  est  prima  h.  e.  per  se  nota  et  indemonstrabilis :  cujus 
idco  praefertur,  evidentia,  quia  (contra  quam  cetera)  sua  luce  est  conspi- 
cua,  et  nihil  indiget  aliena.  Quare,  quae  hanc  adhibet  causam  demon- 
strate, et  habetur  et  nominatur  "  potissima."  Aldrich.  Cf.  also  Whately 
and  Hill. 

2  As  the  puration  of  bile  is  the  cause  to  itself  of  longevity.     Taylor. 

Ex.  1.  Whatever  is  without  bile  is  long-lived 

Every  quadruped  is  without  bile 

.  • .  Every  quadruped  is  long-lived  :  but 

Every  horse  is  a  quadruped 
. '.   Every  horse  is  long-lived. 
8  The  methods  of  explaining  demonstration  and  demonstrative  science 


CHAP.    XIX.]  THE    POSTERIOR   ANALYTICS. 


353 


known,  and  what  is  the  habit  which  recognises 
them,  is  manifest  hence  to  those  who  have  pre- 
viously doubted  it. 

That  it  is  then  impossible  to  have  scientific 
Knowledge  through  demonstration,  without  a 
knowledge  of  first  immediate  principles,  has  been 
elucidated  before,1  still  some  one  may  doubt  the 
knowledge  of  immediate  principles,  both  whether 
it  is  the  same  or  not  the  same,*  also  whether  there 
is  a  science  of  each  or  not,f  or  a  science  of  one, 
but  a  different  kind  (of  science)  of  another,  and 
whether  non-inherent  habits  are  ingenerated,|  or 
when  inherent  are  latent.2  If  then,  indeed,  we 
possess  them,§  it  is  absurd,  for  it  happens  that  it 
(the  principle)  escapes  those  who  have  a  more 
accurate  knowledge  than  demonstration,3  but  if 
not  having  them  before,  we  acquire  them,  how 
can  we  know  and  learn  without  pre-existent 
knowledge  ?  for  this  is  impossible,  as  we  said 
also  in  the  case  of  demonstration.  It  is  evident 
then,  that  they  ||  can  neither  be  possessed,  nor 
ingenerated  in  the  ignorant,   and  in  those  who 

are  identical  therefore  sometimes,  as  in  this  chapter,  demonstration  is 
assumed  for  demonstrative  science. 

1  Vide  book  i.  eh.  2.  We  have  already  noticed  the  two  senses  in  which 
(ifitffog  is  used  by  Aristotle ;  here  it  is  applied  to  a  proposition  not  proved 
by  any  higher  middle  term ;  i.  e.  an  axiomatic  principle,  which  con- 
stitutes the  first  premise  of  a  demonstration:  cf.  An.  Post.  i.  2.  In  An. 
Post.  i.  13,  it  is  applied  to  a  premise  immediate  as  to  its  conclusion. 
Vide  Mansel ;  Aldrich,  p.  104,  note. 

2  As  in  infants.  Aristotle  considered  the  mind  as  a  piece  of  blank 
paper,  on  which  nothing  was  written  but  natural  inclination  (ro  irtQvKoc). 
One  difference  between  disposition  (Siadtcng)  and  habit  (eK'Q),  drawn  in 
the  Categories  and  de  Anima,  (vide  marginal  references,)  consists  in 
considering  habit  more  lasting  than  disposition,  the  former  applying  to 
the  virtues,  etc.,  the  latter  to  heat,  cold,  health,  etc.,  which  last  undergo 
more  rapid  mutation.  The  relation  between  Svvafiig,  ivepytia,  and  t'Eic, 
given  by  Aspasius,  as  quoted  by  Michelet,  is  as  follows  :  Facultas  a  natura 
insita  jam  est  potentia  qua;dam,  sed  nondum  nobis  ut  loquimur  potentia, 
cujus  ex  ipso  vigore  operatio  profluat ;  banc  demum  potentiam  philoso- 
phus  habitum  vocat. 

3  That  is,  the  thing  which  is  known,  or  the  possession  of  the  principle 
itself,  is  concealed  from  children,  who  having  (suppose)  a  knowledge  of 
axioms,  possess  thereby  a  knowledge  more  accurate  than  demonstration. 
Cf.  Waitz. 

2  A 


this  sentence 
to  the  preceding 
chapter.  Bek 
ker  and  Waitz 
as  here. 

1.  Of  the  ne- 
cessity and  me- 
thod of  obtain- 
ing principles 
of  science — cer- 
tain questions 
relative  to  ha- 
bits solved. 
•  With  a 
knowledge  of 
the  conclusion, 
t  i.  e.  of  the 
principle  and  of 
the  conclusion, 
t  i.  e.  are  ac- 
quired.    Cf. 
Eth.  Nic.  lib. 
ii.  ch.  1,  3,  5, 
and  lib.  iii.  5  ; 
also  see  Categ. 
ch.  vi.,  and  de 
Anima,  ii.  1, 
and  ii.  5. 
§  i.  e.  by  na- 
ture. 

II  The  habit  of 
principles. 


354 


Aristotle's  organon. 


[book  n. 


have  no  habit,  wherefore  it  is  necessary  to  possess  a  certain 
power,  yet  not  such  an  one  as  shall  be  more  excellent  ac- 
cording to  accuracy  than  these.  Now  this  ap- 
pears inherent  in  all  animals,  for  they  have  an 
innate  power,  which  they  call  sensible  percep- 
tion,* but  sense  being  inherent  in  some  animals, 
a  permanency  of  the  sensible  object  is  engen- 
5,  et  seq. ;  iii.  i .   <Jered,  but  in  others  it  is  not  engendered.!   Those, 

t   As  insects. 

vide  Tren-  therefore,  wherein  the  sensible  object  does  not  re- 
main, either  altogether  or  about  those  things  which 
do  not  remain,  such  have  no  knowledge  with- 
out sensible  perception,  but  others  when  they  per- 
ceive, retain  one  certain  thing  in  the  soul.J  Now 
since  there  are  many  of  this  kind,  a  certain  differ- 
ence exists,  so  that  with  some,  reason  is  produced 
from  the  permanency  §  of  such  things,])  but  in 
others  it  is  not.^f  From  sense,  therefore,  as  we 
say,  memory  is  produced,  but  from  repeated  re- 
membrance of  the  same  thing,  we  get  experience, 
for  many  remembrances  in  number  constitute 
one  experience.  From  experience,  however,  or 
from  every  universal  being  at  rest  in  the  soul,* 
that  one  besides  the  many,  which  in  all  of  them  is 
one  and  the  same,  the  principle  of  art  and  science 
science'from  arises,  if  indeed  it  is  conversant  with  generation,! 
of  art,  but  if  with  being,  of  science.1  Neither, 
therefore,  are  definite  habits  inherent, J  nor  are 
they  produced  from  other  habits  more  known, 
but  from  sensible  perception,  as  when  a  flight 
occurs  in  battle,  if  one  soldier  makes  a  stand, 

another  stands,  and  then  another,  until  the  fight  is  restored. 


2.  Animals  pos- 
sess sensible 
perception. 
*  alff#i7<Tic.    Cf. 
Eth.  b.  vi.  ch. 
2  and  11  ;  de 
Anima,  b.  ii. 
5 


delen.  de  An 
p.  170,  174. 


I  So  Taylor 
and  Buhle ; 
but  Waitz  and 
Bekker  read 

£T1.      Cf. 

Brundisius. 
§  Waitz  and 
Bekker  read 

UOprKi  but 

Taylor  and 
Buhle,  ui/^utit 
H  As  in  men. 
V  As  in  brutes 

•  i.  e.  remain- 
ing. 

T  With  things 
perishable. 
3.  In  what 
way  we  arrive 
at  a  certain  art 


singulars  sub- 
jected to  the 
senses. 
X  i.  e.  the 
habits  by 
which  princi- 
ples are  known. 


1  Cf.  Trendelenb.  c.  i.  p.  137 ;  Aldrich,  Hill,  and  Mansel  upon  In- 
duction and  Method ;  Zabarella  upon  the  last ;  and  Whately  upon  the 
Province  of  Reasoning.  The  "  methodus  inventionis  "  can  only  be  a 
process  of  inference,  for  no  arrangement  of  parts  is  possible  before  they 
have  been  discovered,  the  discovery  of  general  principles  from  individual 
objects  of  sense,  if  limited  to  the  inferential  process  itself,  will  be  induc- 
tion. The  term,  however,  is  sometimes  extended  so  as  to  include  the 
preliminary  accumulation  of  individuals  :  in  this  under  sense  it  will  em- 
brace the  successive  steps  given  by  Aristotle  here,  of  ai(x8t]<TiG  pvin$y, 
ifiTTEipia,  iTraywyij.  Mansel.  Vide  also  Poetic,  ch.  xvi. ;  De  Anim. 
Proem.  167. 


CHAP.  XIX.]  THE    POSTERIOR    ANALYTICS.  355 

But  the  soul  has  such  a  state  of  being,  as  enables   .  So  as  to  re- 
it  to  suffer  this,*  what,  however,  we  have  before   tain  many  sue. 
said,  but  not  clearly,  let  us  again  explain.     When 
one  thing  without  difference  abides,  there  is  (then)  first,  uni- 
versal in  the  soul,1  (for  the  singular  indeed  is  perceived  by 
sense,  but  sense  is  of  the   universal,  as  of  man,    t  In  these 
but  not  of  the  man  Callias,)  again,  in  these f  it  "^stssP£ 
stops,  till  individuals |  and  universals  stop,§2  as   Taylor!0" 
such   a   kind    of   animal,    until    animal,||   and  in   ^"^  1"' 
this^T  again  (it  stops)  after  a  similar  manner.*   Buhie. ' 
It  is  manifest  then  that  primary  things  become    jj  l^piy^*" 
necessarily  known  to  us  by  induction,  for  thus   permanent  in 
sensible  perception  produces  the  universal.     But   u  Animal, 
since,  of  those  habits  which  are  about  intellect,    *hmTg"|sse°™e~ 
by   which  we  ascertain  truth,  some  are  always   permanent  in 
true,  but  others  admit  the  false,  as  opinion,  and   '^iv°nUg>as 
reasoning,3  but  science,  and  intellect,  are  alwaj's 
true,  and  no  other  kind  of  knowledge,  except  intellect,  is 
more  accurate  than  science,  but   the   principles   of   demon- 
strations are  more  known,  and  all  science  is  connected  with 
reason,  there  could  not  be  a  science  of  principles  :  but  since 
.nothing   can    be   more    true   than    science   except   intellect, 

1  That  is,  the  first  universal  notion,  or  that  which  remains  of  those 
several  things  which  are  perceived  by  tha  senses,  and  which  do  not 
specifically  differ.  From  first  universal  notions,  another  is  formed,  com- 
prehending those  things  which  the  severai  singulars  have  in  common, 
until  summa  genera  are  arrived  at.  The  universal,  of  course,  is  equally 
and  without  difference  found  in  many  particulars. 

*  The  universals  are  so  called  (a/iepri)  because  they  are  inherent  in 
singulars,  not  partially,  but  wholly,  every  where  totally  present  with 
their  participants  :  thus  the  whole  of  animal  is  in  one  man. 

1  Of  the  powers  of  the  soul,  some  are  irrational  and  disobedient  t.i 
reason,  as  the  nutritive,  others  are  capable  of  being  obedient  to  rea- 
son, as  anger  and  desire.  But  other  powers  of  the  soul  are  rational  ; 
and  of  the  rational,  some  are  always  true,  as  intellect  and  science, 
others  are  sometimes  true,  as  opinion  and  Xoyic/xoc,  i.  e.  reasoning  about 
practical  and  political  affairs,  and  things  generable  and  corruptible,  which 
are  in  a  perpetual  flux,  and  are  subject  to  infinite  mutations.  For  in- 
tellect, properly  so  called,  is  that  power  or  summit  of  the  soul  which 
energizes  about  things  that  possess  an  invariable  sameness  of  subsistence. 
Taylor.  Vide  also  Trendelenb.de  An.  iii.  c.  4 — 6;  Biese  i.  p.  327  ; 
Rassow,  p.  73.  And  cf.  Eth.  Nic.  b.  i.  c.  13,  Bonn's  ed.,  where  see 
Browne's  note ;  Poetics,  c.  16:  Magna  Moral,  i.  31;  and  Eudem.  Ti. 
et  lib.  v.  c.  3,  et  seq. 


S56  Aristotle's  organon.  [book  11. 

intellect  will  belong  to  principles,  and  to  those 
who  consider  from  these  it  is  evident  also,  that  as 
demonstration  is  not  the  principle  of  demonstra- 
tion, so  neither  is  science  the  principle  of  science. 
If  then  we  have  no  other  true  genus  (of  habit) 
besides  science,  intellect  will  be  the  principle  of 
•   science  :  it  will  also  be  the  principle  (of  the  know- 
the  principle,   but  all  this  subsists  similarly  with 
every  thing. 


4.  Intelle:t 
alone  conver- 
sant with,  and 
itself  the  prin- 
ciple of  science 
AiJ  science 
through  de- 
monstration 
knows  the  ob- 
jects of  science 

ledge)  of 
respect  to 


END   OF   VOL.    I. 


IONDON ; 


PaWTED  BY   WILLIAM  CLOWE9  AND  SONS,   LIMITED,   STAMFORD  STREET 
AND   CHARING   CROSS. 


4 


CATALOGUE   OF 

BONN'S    LIBRARIES. 

740  Volumes,  £"158   19^.  6d. 


u 


The  Publishers  are  new  issuing  the  Libraries  in  a  NEW  AND 
MORE  ATTRACTIVE  STYLE  OF  BINDING.  The  original 
bindings  endeared  to  many  book-lovers  by  association  will  still  be 
kept  in  stock,  but  henceforth  all  orders  will  be  executed  in  the  New 
binding,  unless  the  contrary  is  expressly  staled. 


New  Volumes  of  Standard  Works  in  the  various  branches  of 
Literature  are  constantly  being  added  to  this  Series,  which  is 
already  unsurpassed  in  respect  to  the  number,  variety,  and  clieapness 
of  the  Works  contained  in  it.  The  Publishers  beg  to  announce  the 
following  Volumes  as  recently  issued  or  now  in  preparation  : — 

Goethe's  Faust.  Part  I.  The  Original  Text,  with  Hayward's  Translation 
and  Notes,  carefully  revised,  with  an  Introduction  and  Bibliography,  by  C.  A.  Buch- 
heim,  Ph.D.,  Professor  of  German  Language  and  Literature  at  King's  College, 
London.  [In  the  Press. 

Arthur  Young's  Tour  in  Ireland.     Edited  by  A.  W.  Hutton,  Librarian, 

National  Liberal  Club.  [Preparing. 

Ricardo  on  the  Principles  of  Political  Economy  and  Taxation.     Edited 

with  Notes  by  E.  C.  K.  Gonner,  M.A.,  Lecturer,  University  College,  Liverpool. 

[See/.  19. 

Schopenhauer's  Essays.     Selected  and  Translated.     By  E.  Belfort  Bax. 

[See  p.  9. 

Voltaire's  Tales.     Translated  by  R.  B.  Boswell.     Vol.1,     y.  6J.       [Seep.S. 
Count    Grammont's   Memoirs   of  the    Court    of  Charles  II.     With  the 

Boscobel  Tracts,  &c.     New  Edition.     3s.  6d.  [See p.  5. 

Gray's  Letters.     New  Edition.     Edited  by  the  Rev.  D.  C.  Tovey,  M.A. 

\_In  the  press. 

Schools  and  Masters  of  Fence.  By  C.  Egerton  Castle.  New  Edition. 
With  numerous  Illustrations.  [In  the  press. 

Montaigne's  Essays.     Cotton's  Translation,  revised  by  \V.  C.  Ilazlitt.    New- 
Edition.     3  Vols.  [In  the  press. 

Descartes'  Principal   Works.      Edited  by  Professor  G.    Croom    Robertson 
and  Thomas  YVhittaker.     2  Vols. 

Hartley  Coleridge's  Essays  and  Marginalia.  Edited  by  the  Lord  Chief 
Justice.  [Preparing. 

Hoffmann's  Works.     Translated  by  Lieut.-Colonel  Evving.     Vol.  II. 

[In  the  pins. 

Bohn's  Handbooks  of  Games.  New  enlarged  edition.  In  2  vols. 

[See  p.  21. 
Vol.  I. — Table  Games,  by  Major-General  Drayson,  R.A.,  R.  F.  Green,  and  'Berkeley.' 
II.— Card  Games,  by  Dr.  W.  role,  F.R.S.,  R.  F.  Green,  'Berkeley,   and   Baxter- 
Wray. 

Bohn's  Handbooks  of  Athletic  Sports.     S  Vols.  [See p.  21. 


For  BOHNS  SELECT  LIBRARY,  seep.  23. 


3 


November,  1891. 


BOHN'S     LIBRARIES. 


STANDARD    LIBRARY. 

338  Vols,  at  $s.  6d.  each,  excepting  those  marked  otherwise.     (59;.  17s.  6J.) 


ADDISON'S  "Works.  Notes  of  Bishop 
Hurd.  Short  Memoir,  Portrait,  and  8 
Plates  of  Medals.     6  vols. 

This  is    the  most  complete    edition   of 
Addison's  Works  issued. 

ALFIERI'S  Tragedies.  In  English 
Verse.  With  Notes,  Arguments,  and  In- 
troduction, by  E.  A.  Bowring,  C.B.   2  vols. 

AMERICAN  POETRT.  —  See  Poetry 
of America. 

■BACON'S    Moral    and    Historical 

Works,  including  Essays,  Apophthegms, 
Wisdom  of  the  Ancients,  New  Atlantis, 
Henry  VII.,  Henry  VIII.,  Elizabeth, 
Henry  Prince  of  Wales,  History  of  Great 
Britain,  Julius  Caesar,  and  Augustus  Caesar. 
With  Critical  and  Biographical  Introduc- 
tion and  Notes  by  J.  Devey,  M.A.  Por- 
trait. 

— —  See  also  Philosophical  Library. 

•BALLADS  AND  SONGS  of  the  Pea- 
santry of  England,  from  Oral  Recitation, 
private  MSS.,  Broadsides,  &c.  Edit,  by 
R.  Bell. 

BEAUMONT       AND       FLETCHER. 

Selections.     With  Notes  and  Introduction 
by  Leigh  Hunt. 

vBECKMANN  (J.)  History  Of  Inven- 
tions, Discoveries,  and  Origins.  With 
Portraits  of  Beckmann  and  James  Watt. 
2  vols. 

BELL  (Robert).—  St*  Ballads,  C/taucer, 
Gretn. 

<BOSWELL'S  Life  of  Johnson,  with 
the  TOUR  in  the  HEBRIDES  an  1 
JOHNSONIANA.  New  Edition,  with 
Notes  and  Appendices,  by  the  Rev.  A. 
Napier,  M.A.,  Trinity  College,  Cam- 
bridge, Vicar  of  Holkham,  Editor  of  the 
Cambridge  Edition  of  the  '  Theological 
Works  of  Barrow.'  With  Frontispiece  to 
each  vol.     6  vols. 

.BREMER'S       (Frederika)      Works. 
Trans,  by  M.  Howitt.  Portrait.  4  vc's. 


BRINK  (B.  ten).  Early  English 
Literature  (to  Wiclif).  By  Bernhard  ten 
Brink.     Trans,  by  Prof.  H.  M.  Kennedy. 

BROWNE'S   (Sir    Thomas)   Works. 

Edit,   by   S.   Wilkin,  with  Dr.  Johnson's 
Life  of  Browne.     Portrait.     3  vols. 

BURKE'S  Works.    6  vols. 

Speeches  on  the  Impeachment 

of  Warren  Hastings  ;  and  Letters.     2  vols. 

Life.    By  Sir  J.  Prior.     Portrait. 

BURNS  (Robert).  Life  of.  By  J.  G. 
Lockhart,  D.C.L.  A  new  and  enlarged 
edition.  With  Notes  and  Appendices  by 
W.  Scott  Douglas.     Portrait. 

BUTLER'S  (Bp.)  Analogy  of  Reli- 
gion, Natural  and  Revealed,  to  the  Con- 
stitution and  Course  of  Nature  ;  with  Two 
Dissertations  on  Identity  and  Virtue,  and 
Fifteen  Sermons.  With  Introductions, 
Notes,  and  Memoir.     Portrait. 

CAMOEN'S  Lusiad,  or  the  Discovery 
of  India.  An  Epic  Poem.  Trans,  from 
the  Portuguese,  with  Dissertation,  His- 
torical Sketch,  and  Life,  by  W.  J.  Mickle. 
5th  edition. 

CARAFAS     (The)     of     Maddalonl. 

Naples  under  Spanish  Dominion.  Trans, 
from  the  German  of  Alfred  de  Reumont. 
Portrait  of  Massaniello. 

CARREL.    The  Counter-Revolution 

in  England  for  the  Re-establishment  of 
Popery  under  Charles  II.  and  James  II., 
by  Armand  Carrel  ;  with  Fox's  History  of 
James  II.  and  Lord  Lonsdale's  Memoir  of 
James  II.     Portrait  of  Carrel. 

CARRUTHERS.  —  Set  Pop*,  in  lUus- 
traled  Library. 

CART'S  Dante.  The  Vision  of  Hell, 
Purgatory,  and  Paiadise.  Trans,  by  Rev. 
H.  F.  Cary,  M.A.  With  Life,  Chronolo- 
gical View  of  his  Age,  Notes,  and  Index 
of  Proper  Names.     Portrait. 

This  is  the  authentic  edition,  containing 
Mr.  Gary's  last  corrections,  with  additional 
notes. 


BOHN'S  LI BR ARIES. 


CELLINI  (Benvenuto).    Memoirs  of, 

by  himself.     With  Notes  of  G.  P.  Carpani. 
Trans,  by  T.  Roscoe.     Portrait. 

CERVANTES'    Galatea.      A    Pastoral 
Romance.    Trans,  by  G.  W.  J.  Gyll. 


—   Exemplary 

W.  K.  Kelly. 


Novels.      Trans,    by 


Don    Quixote    de    la    Mancha. 

Motteux's  Translation  revised.  With  Lock- 
hart's  Life  and  Notes.     2  vols. 

CHAUCER'S  Poetical  •Works.  With 
Poems  formerly  attributed  to  him.  With  a 
Memoir,  Introduction,  Notes,  and  a  Glos- 
saryj  by  R.  Bell.  Improved  edition,  with 
Preliminary  Essay  by  Rev.  W.  W.  Skeat, 
M.A.     Portrait.     4  vols. 

CLASSIC  TALES,  containing  Rasselas, 
Vicar  of  Wakefield,  Gulliver's  Travels,  and 
The  Sentimental  Journey. 

COLERIDGE'S  (S.  T.)  Friend.  A  Series 
of  Essays  on  Morals,  Politics,  and  Reli- 
gion.   Portrait. 

Aids  to  Reflection.    Confessions 

of  an  Inquiring  Spirit ;  and  Essays  on 
Faith  and  the  Common  Prayer-book.  New 
Edition,  revised. 

-  Table-Talk   and   Omnlana.    By 

T.  Ashe,  B.A. 

Lectures  on  Shakespeare   and 

other  Poets.    Edit,  by  T.  Ashe,  B.A. 

Containing  the  lectures  taken  down  in 
1811-12  by  J.  P.  Collier,  and  those  de- 
livered at  Bristol  in  1813. 

Blograpbia  Literaria;  or,  Bio- 
graphical Sketches  of  my  Literary  Life 
and   Opinions ;   with  Two   Lay  Sermons. 

;  Miscellanies,    .Esthetic    and 

Literary  ;  to  which  is  added,  The  Theory 
of  Life.  Collected  and  arranged  by 
T.  Ashe,  B.A. 

COMMINES.— See  Philip. 

CONDE'S  History  of  the  Dominion 

of  the  Arabs  in  Spain.  Trans,  by  Mrs. 
Foster.  Portrait  of  Abderahmen  ben 
Moavia.     3  vols. 

COWPER'SCompleteWorks,  Poems, 

Correspondence,  and  Translations.  Edit. 
with_  Memoir  by  R.  Southey.  45  En- 
gravings.   8  vols. 

COXE'S  Memoirs   of  the  Duke  of 

Marlborough.  With  his  original  Corre- 
spondence, from  family  records  at  Blen- 
heim. Revised  edition.  Portraits.  3  vols. 
***  An  Atlas  of  the  plans  of  Marl- 
borough's campaigns,  4to.  10.?.  6d. 


COXE'S   History  of  the   House  of 

Austria.  From  the  Foundation  of  the 
Monarchy  by  Rhodolph  of  Hapsburgh  to 
the  Death  of  Leopold  II.,  1218-1792.  By 
Archdn.  Coxe.  With  Continuation  from 
the  Accession  of  Francis  I.  to  the  Revolu- 
tion of  1848.     4  Portraits.    4  vols. 

CUNNINGHAM'S  Lives  of  the  most 

Eminent  British  Painters.  With  Notes 
and  16  fresh  Lives  by  Mrs.  Heaton.   3  vols. 

DEFOE'S  Novels  and  Miscellaneous 

Works.  With  Prefaces  and  Notes,  in- 
cluding those  attributed  to  Sir  W.  Scott. 
Portrait.     7  vols. 

DE  LOLME'S  Constitution  of  Eng. 

land,  in  which  it  is  compared  both  with  the 
Republican  form  of  Government  and  the 
other  Monarchies  of  Europe.  Edit.,  with 
Life  and  Notes,  by  J.  Macgregor. 

DUNLOP'S  History  of  Fiction.    New 

Edition,  revised.  By  Henry  Wilson. 
2  yols.,  5^.  each. 

EDGEWORTH'S  Stories  for  Chil- 
dren.   With  8  Illustrations  by  L.  Speed. 

ELZE'S  Shakespeare.- .SW  Shakespeare 

EMERSON'S  "Works.    3  vols. 

Vol.  I.  —Essays,  Lectures,  and  Poems. 

Vol.  II.— English  Traits,  Nature,  and 
Conduct  of  Life. 

Vol.  III.— Society  and  Solitude— Letters 
and  Social  Aims — Miscellaneous  Papers 
(hitherto  uncollected)— May-Day,  &c. 

FOSTER'S  (John)  Life  and  Corre- 
spondence. Edit,  by  J.  E.  Ryland.  Por- 
trait.    2  vols. 

Lectures  at  Broadmead  Chapel. 

Edit,  by  J.  E.  Ryland.     2  vols. 

Critical   Essays  contributed  to 

the  '  Eclectic   Review,"      Edit,   by  J.  E. 
Ryland.     2  vols. 

Essays :  On  Decision  of  Charac- 
ter ;  on  a  Man's  writing  Memoirs  of  Him- 
self; on  the  epithet  Romantic ;  on  the 
aversion  of  Men  of  Taste  to  Evangelical 
Religion. 

Essays  on  the  Evils  of  Popular 

Ignorance,  and  a  Discourse  on  the  Propa- 
gation of  Christianity  in  India. 

•  Essay  on  the  Improvemen     of 

Time,   with  Notes  of  Sermons  and  ether 
Pieces. 

Fosteriana :  selected  from  periodical 

papers,  edit,  by  H.  G.  Bohn. 

FOX  (Rt.  Hon.  C.  J.)— See  Carrel. 


STANDARD  LIBRARY. 


GIBBON'S  Decline  and  Fall  of  the 

Roman  Empire.  Complete  and  unabridged, 
with  variorum  Notes  ;  including  those  of 
Guizot,  Wenck,  Niebuhr,  Hugo,  Neander, 
and  others.     7  vols.     2  Maps  and  Portrait. 

GOETHE'S  Works.  Trans,  into  English 
by  E.  A.  Bowring,  C.B.,  Anna  Swanwick, 
Sir  Walter  Scott,  &c.  &c.     14  vols. 

Vols.  I.  and  II. — Autobiography  and  An- 
nals.    Portrait. 

Vol.  III.— Faust.     Complete. 

Vol.  IV. — Novels  and  Tales  :  containing 
Elective  Affinities,  Sorrows  of  Werther, 
The  German  Emigrants,  The  Good  Wo- 
men, and  a  Nouvelette. 

Vol.  V. — Wilhelm  Meister's  Apprentice- 
ship. 

Vol.  VI. — Conversations  with  Eckerman 
and  Soret. 

Vol.  VII. — Poems  and  Ballads  in  the  ori- 
ginal Metres,  including  Hermann  and 
Dorothea. 

Vol.  VIII.— Gotz  von  Berlichingen,  Tor- 
quato  Tasso,  Egmont,  Iphigenia,  Clavigo, 
WayVard  Lover,  and  Fellow  Culprits. 

Vol.  IX. —  Wilhelm  Meister's  Travels. 
Complete  Edition. 

Vol.  X.  —  Tour  in  Italy.  Two  Parts. 
And  Second  Residence  in  Rome. 

Vol.  XI. — Miscellaneous  Travels,  Letters 
from  Switzerland,  Campaign  in  France, 
Siege  of  Mainz,  and  Rhine  Tour. 

Vol.  XII. — Early  and  Miscellaneous 
Letters,  including  Letters  to  his  Motker, 
with  Biography  and  Notes. 

Vol.  XIII. — Correspondence  with  Zelter. 

Vol.  XIV.-  Reineke  Fox,  West-Eastern 
Divan  and  Achilleid.  Translated  in 
original  metres  by  A.  Rogers. 

Correspondence  with   Schiller. 

2  vols. — See  Schiller. 

— —  Faust. — See  Collegiate  Series. 

GOLDSMITH'S  Works.    5  vols. 

Vol.  I  .—Life,  Vicar  of  Wakefield ,  Essays , 
and  Letters. 

Vol.  II.— Poems,  Plays,  Bee,  Cock  Lane 
Ghost. 

Vol.  III.— The  Citizen  of  the  World, 
Polite  Learning  in  Europe. 

Vol.  IV. — Biographies,  Criticisms,  Later 
Essays. 

Vol.  V.  — Prefaces,  Natural  History, 
Letters,  Goody  Two-Shoes,  Index. 

GRAMMONT  (Count).  Memoirs  of 
the  Court  of  Charles  II.  With  the  Bos- 
cobel  Tracts,  &c.     New  Edition. 

GREENE,    MARLOWE,     and    BEN 

JONSON  (Poems  of).     With  Notes  and 
Memoirs  by  R.  Bell. 

GREGORY'S    (Dr.)    The   Evidences, 

Doctrines,  and  Duties  of  the  Christian  Re- 
ligion. 


GRIMM'S  Household  Tales.  With  the 
Original  Notes.  Trans,  by  Mrs.  A.  Hunt. 
Introduction  by  Andrew  Lang,  M.A.  2 
vols. 

GUIZOT'S  History  of  Representative 

Government  in  Europe.    Trans,  by  A.  R. 
Scoble. 

English  Revolution  of  16  40.  From 

the  Accession  of  Charles  I.  to  his  Death. 
Trans,  by  W.  Hazlitt.     Portrait. 

History  of  Civilisation.    From  the 

Roman  Empire  to  the  French  Revolution. 
Trans,  by  W.  Hazlitt.     Portraits.     3  vols. 

HALL'S   (Rev.  Robert)  Works  and 

Remains.  Memoir  by  Dr.  Gregory  and 
Essay  by  J.  Foster.     Portrait. 

HAUFF'S  Tales.  The  Caravan  — The 
Sheikh  of  Alexandria  —  The  Inn  in  the 
Spessart.     Translated  by  Prof.  S.  Mendel. 

HAWTHORNE'S  Tales.    3  vols. 

Vol.  I.— Twice-told  Tales,  and  the  Snow 
Image. 

Vol.  II.— Scarlet  Letter,  and  the  House 
with  Seven  Gables. 

Vol.  III.— Transformation,  and  Blithe- 
dale  Romance. 

HAZUTT'S  (W.)  Works.   7  vols. 
Table-Talk. 

The  Literature   of  the  Age    of 

Elizabeth  and  Characters  of  Shakespeare's 
Plays. 

English  Poets  and  English  Comic 

Writers. 

The  Plain  Speaker.    Opinions  on 

Books,  Men,  and  Things. 

Round     Table.      Conversations     of 

James  Northcote,  R.A.  ;   Characteristics. 

Sketches  and  Essays,  and  Winter- 
slow. 

Spirit   of  the   Age;    or,  Contem- 

porary  Portraits.  New  Edition,  by  W. 
Carew  Hazlitt. 

HEINE'S  Poems.  Translated  in  the 
original  Metres,  with  Life  by  E.  A.  Bow- 
ring,  C.B. 

Travel-Pictures.    The  Tour  in  the 

Harz,  Norderney,  and  Book  of  Ideas,  to- 
gether with  the  Romantic  School.  Trans, 
by  F.  Storr.     With  Maps  and  Appendices. 

HOFFMANN'S  Works.  The  Serapion 
Brethren.  Vol.  I.  Trans,  by  Lt.-Col. 
Ewing.  [Vol.  II.  in  the  press. 

HOOPER'S     (G.)     Waterloo  :     The 

Downfall  of  the  First  Napoleon  :  a  His- 
tory of  the  Campaign  of  1S15.  By  George 
Hooper.  With  Maps  and  Plans.  New 
Edition,  revised. 


6 


BONN'S  LIBRARIES. 


HUGO'S  (Victor)  Dramatic  Works.    ] 

Hernani— RuyBlas— The  King's  Diversion. 
Translated  by  Mrs.  Newton  Crosland  and 
F.  L.  Slous. 

Poems,  chiefly  Lyrical.     Collected  by 

H.  L.  Williams. 

HUNGARY:  its  History  and  Revo- 
lution, with  Memoir  of  Kossuth.    Portrait. 

HUTCHINSON    (Colonel).    Memoirs 

of.  By  his  Widow,  with  her  Autobio- 
graphy, and  the  Siege  of  Lathom  House. 
Portrait. 

IRVTNG'S    (Washington)    Complete 

Works.     15  vols. 

Life  and  Letters.    By  his  Nephew, 

Pierre  E.  Irving.  With  Index  and  a 
Portrait.     2  vols. 

JAMES'S  (G.  P.  R.)  Life  of  Richard 

Cceur  de  Lion.    Portraits  of  Richard  and 
Philip  Augustus.    2  vols. 
Louis  XIV.    Portraits.    2  vols. 

JAMESON    (Mrs.)      Shakespeare's 

Heroines.  Characteristics  of  Women.  By 
Mrs.  Jameson. 

JEAN  PAUL.— See  Richter. 

JOHNSON'S    Lives    of    the    Poets. 

Edited,  with  Notes,  by  Mrs.  Alexander 
Napier.  And  an  Introduction  by  Pro- 
fessor J.  W.  Hales,  M.A.     3  vols. 

JONSON  (Ben).  Yo%m.&oi.— Sec  Greene. 

JOSEPHUS  (Flavius),  The  Works  of. 

Whiston's  Translation.  Revised  by  Rev. 
A.  R.  Shilleto,  M.A.  With  Topographical 
and  Geographical  Notes  by  Colonel  Sir 
C.  W.  Wilson,  K.C.B.     5  vols. 

JUNIUS 'S  Letters.  With  Woodfall's 
Notes.  An  Essay  on  the  Authorship.  Fac- 
similes of  Handwriting.     2  vols. 

LA  FONTAINE'S  Fables.  In  English 
Verse,  with  Essay  on  the  Fabulists.  By 
Elizur  Wright. 

LAMARTINE'S   The    Girondists,  or 

Personal  Memoirs  of  the  Patriots  of  the 
French  Revolution.  Trans,  by  H.  T. 
Ryde.  Portraits  of  Robespierre,  Madame 
Roland,  and  Charlotte  Corday.     3  vols. 

— —  The    Restoration   of  Monarchy 

in  France  (a  Sequel  to  The  Girondists). 
5  Portraits.     4  vols. 

The  French  Revolution  of  1848. 

Portraits. 

LAMB'S  (Charles)  Ella  and  Eliana. 

Complete  Edition.     Portrait. 


LAMB'S     (Charles)     Specimens     of 

English  Dramatic  Poets  of  the  time  of 
Elizabeth.  With  Notes  and  the  Extracts 
from  the  Garrick  Plays. 

Talfourd's   Letters  of  Charles 

Lamb.  New  Edition,  by  W.  Carew 
Hazlitt.    2  vols. 

LANZI'S   History   of  Painting   in 

Italy,  from  the  Period  of  the  Revival  of 
the  Fine  Arts  to  the  End  of  the  18th 
Century.  With  Memoir  and  Portraits. 
Trans,  by  T.  Roscoe.     3  vols. 

LAPPENBERG'S  England  under  the 

Anglo-Saxon  Kings.  Trans,  by  B.Thorpe, 
F.S.A.     2  vols. 

LESSING'S  Dramatic  Works.  Com- 
plete. By  E.  Bell,  M.A.  With  Memoir 
by  H.  Zimmern.     Portrait.     2  vols. 

Laokoon,  Dramatic  Notes,  and 

Representation  of  Death  by  the  Ancients. 
Trans,  by  E.  C.  Beasley  and  Helen 
Zimmern.     Frontispiece. 

LOCKE'S  Philosophical  Works,  con- 
taining Human  Understanding,Controversy 
with  Bishop  of  Worcester,  Malebranche's 
Opinions,  Natural  Philosophy,  Reading 
and  Study.  With  Introduction,  Analysis, 
and  Notes,  by  J.  A.  St.  John.  Portrait. 
2  vols. 

— -  Life  and  Letters,  with  Extracts  from 
his  Common-place  Books.     By  Lord  King. 

LOCKHART  (J.  G.)-See  Bums. 

LUTHER'S  Table-TaUs.  Trans,  by  W. 
Hazlitt.  With  Life  by  A.  Chalmers,  and 
Luther's  Catechism.  Portrait  after 
Cranach. 

Autobiography.— See  Michelet. 

MACHIAVELLI'S  History  of  Flo- 
rence, The  Prince,  Savonarola,  Historical 
Tracts,  and  Memoir.     Portrait. 

MARLOWE.    Poems  of.— See  Greene. 

MARTTNEAU'S     (Harriet)    History 

of  England  (including  History  of  the  Peace) 
from  1800-1846.     5  vols. 

MEN Z EL'S   History   of  Germany, 

from  the  Earliest  Period  to  the  Crimean 
War.        Portraits.     3  vols. 

MICHELET'S  Autobiography  of 
Luther.  Trans,  by  W.  Hazlitr.  With 
Notes. 

The  French   Revolution   to   the 

Flight  of  the  King  in  1791.     Frontispiece. 

MIGNET'S  The  French  Revolution, 

from  1789  to  1814.     Portrait  of  Napoleon. 


STANDARD  LIBRARY. 


MILTON'S  Pros©  Works.  With  Pre- 
face, Preliminary  Remarks  by  J.  A.  St. 
John,  and  Index.     5  vols.     Portraits. 

Poetical  Works.    With  120  Wood 

Engravings.     2  vols. 

MITFORD'S    (Miss)    Onr   Village. 

Sketches  of  Rural  Character  and  Scenery. 
2  Engravings.     2  vols. 

MOLTERE'S    Dramatic    Works.     In 

English  Prose,  by  C.  H.  Wall.  With  a 
Life  and  a  Portrait.     3  vols. 

'  It  is  not  too  much  to  say  that  we  have 
here  probably  as  good  a  translation  of 
Moliere  as  can  be  given.' — Academy. 

MONTAGU.    Letters  and  Works  of 

Lady  Mary  Wortley  Montagu.  Lord 
Wharncliffe's  Third  Edition.  Edited  by 
W.  Moy  Thomas.  New  and  revised 
edition.  With  steel  plates.  2  vols.  5s. 
each. 

MONTESQUIEU'S    Spirit   of  Laws. 

Revised  Edition,  with  D'Alembert's  Analy- 
sis, Notes,  and  Memoir.     2  vols. 

NEANDER   (Dr.  A.)    History  of  the 

Christian  Religion  and  Church.  Trans,  by 
J.  Torrey.     With  Short  Memoir.     10  vols. 

Life  of  Jesus  Christ,  in  its  His- 
torical Connexion  and  Development. 

The   Planting  and  Training  of 

the  Christian  Church  by  the  Apostles. 
With  the  Antignosticus,  or  Spirit  of  Ter- 
tullian.    Trans,  by  J.  E.  Ryland.     2  vols. 

Lectures     on     the    History    of 

Christian  Dogmas.  Trans,  by  J.  E.  Ry- 
land.    2  vols. 

Memorials  of  Christian  Life  In 

the  Early  and  Middle  Ages ;  including 
Light  in  Dark  Places.  Trans,  by  J.  E. 
Ryland. 

NORTH'S  Lives  of  the  Right  Hon. 

Francis  North,  Baron  Guildford,  the  Hon. 
Sir  Dudley  North,  and  the  Hon.  and  Rev. 
Dr.  John  North.  By  the  Hon.  Roger 
North.  Edited  by  A.  Jessopp,  D.D.  With 
3  Portraits.     3  vols.     3.1.  6rf.  each.  _ 

'  Lovers  of  good  literature  will  rejoice  at 
the  appearance  of  a  new,  handy,  and  com- 
plete edition  of  so  justly  famous  a  book, 
and  will  congratulate  themselves  that  it 
has  found  so  competent  and  skilful  an 
editor  as  Dr.  Jessopp.' — Times. 

OCKLEY  (S.)  History  of  the  Sara- 
cens and  their  Conquests  in  Syria,  Persia, 
and  Egypt.  Comprising  the  Lives  of 
Mohammed  and  his  Successors  to  the 
Death  of  Abdalmelik,  the  Eleventh  Caliph. 
By  Simon  Ockley,  B.D.,  Portrait  of  Mo- 
hammed. 

PASCAL'S  Thoughts.  Translated  from 
the  Text  of  M.  Auguste  Molinier  by 
C.  Kegan  Paul.    3rd  edition. 


PERCY'S  Reliques  of  Ancient  Eng^ 

lish  Poetry,  consisting  of  Ballads,  Songs, 
and  other  Pieces  of  our  earlier  Poets,  with 
some  few  of  later  date.  With  Essay  on 
Ancient  Minstrels,  and  Glossary.     2  vols. 

PHILIP   DE  COMMTNES.    Memoirs 

of.  Containing  the  Histories  of  Louis  XI. 
and  Charles  VIII.,  and  Charles  the  Bold, 
Duke  of  Burgundy.  With  the  History  of 
Louis  XL,  by  Jean  de  Troyes.  Trans- 
lated, with  a  Life  and  Notes,  by  A.  R. 
Scoble.     Portraits.     2  vols. 

PLUTARCH'S  LIVES.  Translated,  with. 
Notes  and  Life,  by  A.  Stewart,  M.A., 
late  Fellow  of  Trinity  College,  Cambridge, 
and  G.  Long,  M.A.     4  vols. 

POETRY  OF  AMERICA.    Selections 

from  One  Hundred  Poets,  from  1776  to 
1876.  With  Introductory  Review,  and 
Specimens  of  Negro  Melody,  by  W.  J. 
Linton.     Portrait  of  W.  Whitman. 

RACINE'S  (Jean)  Dramatic  Works.. 

A  metrical  English  version,  with  Bio- 
graphical notice.  By  R.  Bruce  Boswell, 
M.A.  Oxon.     2  vols. 

RASTKE  (L.)    History  of  the  Popes, 

their  Church  and  State,  and  their  Conflicts 
with  Protestantism  in  the  16th  and  17th 
Centuries.  Trans,  by  E.  Foster.  Portraits. 
3  vols. 

History  of  Servia.    Trans,  by  Mrs. 

Kerr.  To  which  is  added,  The  Slave  Pro- 
vinces of  Turkey,  by  Cyprien  Robert. 

History  of  the  Latin  and  Teu- 
tonic Nations.  1494-1514.  Trans.  _  by 
P.  A.  Ashworth,  translator  of  Dr.  Gneist's 
•History  of  the  English  Constitution.' 

REUMONT  (Alfred  de).-See  Cara/as. 

REYNOLDS'  (Sir  J.)  Literary  Works. 

With  Memoir  and  Remarks  by  H.  W. 
Beechy.     2  vols. 

RICHTER   (Jean    Paul).     Levana, 

a  Treatise  on  Education  ;  together  with  the 
Autobiography,  and  a  short  Memoir. 

Flower,  Fruit,  and  Thorn  Pieces, 

or  the  Wedded  Life,  Death,  and  Marriage 

of  Siebenkaes.  Translated  by  Alex.  Ewing. 

The  only  complete  English  translation. 

ROSCOE'S  (W.)  Life  of  Leo  X.,  with 
Notes,  Historical  Documents,  and  Disser- 
tation on  Lucretia  Borgia.  3  Portraits. 
2  vols. 

Lorenzo    de'  Medici,  called    'The 

Magnificent,'  with  Copyright  Notes, 
Poems,  Letters,  &c.  With  Memoir  of 
Roscoe  and  Portrait  of  Lorenzo. 

RUSSIA,     History    of,    from    tho 

earliest  Period  to  the  Crimean  War.  By 
W.  K.  Kelly.     3  Portraits.     2  vols. 


BOHN'S  LIBRARIES. 


SCHILLER'S  Works.    7  vols. 

Vol.  I.— History  of  theThirty  Years'  War. 
Rev.  A.  J.  W.  Morrison,  M.A.     Portrait. 

Vol.  II.— History  of  the  Revolt  in  the 
Netherlands,  the  Trials  of  Counts  Egmont 
and  Horn,  the  Siege  of  Antwerp,  and  the 
Disturbance  of  France  preceding  the  Reign 
of  Henry  IV.  Translated  by  Rev.  A.  J.  W. 
Morrison  and  L.  Dora  Schmitz. 

Vol.  III.— Don  Carlos.  R.  D.  Boylan 
—Mary  Stuart.  Mellish  —  Maid  of  Or- 
leans. Anna  Swanwick — Bride  of  Mes- 
sina. A.  Lodge,  M.A.  Together  with  the 
Use  of  the  Chorus  in  Tragedy  (a  short 
Essay).     Engravings. 

These  Dramas  are  all  translated  in  metre. 

Vol.  IV. — Robbers — Fiesco — Love  and 
Intrigue — Demetrius — Ghost  Seer — Sport 
of  Divinity. 

The  Dramas  in  this  volume  are  in  prose. 

Vol.  V.— Poems.     E.  A.  Bowring,  C.B. 

Vol.  VI.— Essays,  ^Esthetical  and  Philo- 
sophical, including  the  Dissertation  on  the 
Connexion  between  the  Animal  and  Spiri- 
tual in  Man. 

Vol.  VII.  — Wallenstein's  Camp.  J. 
Churchill.  —  Piccolomini  and  Death  of 
Wallenstein.  S.  T.  Coleridge.— William 
Tell.  Sir  Theodore  Martin,  K.C.B.,  LL.D. 

SCHILLER  and  GOETHE.  Corre- 
spondence between,  from  a.d.  1794-1805. 
Trans,  by  L.  Dora  Schmitz.     2  vols. 

SCHLEGEL    (F.)      Lectures    on  the 

Philosophy  of  Life  and  the  Philosophy  of 
Language.     Trans,  by  A.  J.  W.  Morrison. 

— —  The  History  of  Literature,  Ancient 

and  Modern. 

—  The  Philosophy  of  History.  With 

Memoir  and  Portrait.  Trans,  by  J.  B. 
Robertson. 

Modern  History,  with  the  Lectures 

entitled  Caesar  and  Alexander,  and  The 
Beginning  of  our  History.  Translated  by 
L.  Purcell  and  R.  H.  Whitelock. 

./Esthetic    and    Miscellaneous 

Works,  containing  Letters  on  Christian 
Art,  Essay  on  Gothic  Architecture,  Re- 
marks on  the  Romance  Poetry  of  the  Mid- 
dle Ages,  on  Shakspeare,  the  Limits  of  the 
Beautiful,  and  on  the  Language  and  Wis- 
dom of  the  Indians.     By  E.  J.  Millington. 

SCHLEGEL   (A.  W.)    Dramatic  Art 

and  Literature.  By  J.  Black.  With  Me- 
moir by  Rev.  A.  J.  W.  Morrison.    Portrait. 

SCHUMANN  (Robert),  His  Life  and 
Works.  By  A.  Reissmann.  Trans,  by 
A.  L.  Alger. 

Early  Letters.    Translated  by  May 

Herbert.    With  Preface  by  Sir  G.  Grove. 

'SHAKESPEARE'S    Dramatio   Art. 

The  History  and  Character  of  Shakspeare's 
Plays.  By  Dr.  H.  Ulrici.  Trans,  by  L. 
Dora  Schmitz.     2  vols. 


SHAKESPEARE  (William).  A 
Literary  Biography  by  Karl  Elze,  Ph.D., 
LL.D.  Translated  by  L.  Dora  Schmitz.  $s. 

SHERIDAN'S  Dramatic  Works.  With 
Memoir.    Portrait  (after  Reynolds). 

SISMONDI'S  History  of  the  Litera- 
ture of  the  South  of  Europe.  Trans,  by 
T.  Roscoe.     Portraits.     2  vols. 

SMITH'S  (Adam)  Theory  of  Moral 

Sentiments  ;  with  Essay  on  the  First  For- 
mation of  Languages,  and  Critical  Memoir 
by  Dugald  Stewart. 

See  Economic  Library. 

SMYTH'S   (Professor)  Lectures    on 

Modern  History  ;  from  the  Irruption  of  the 
Northern  Nations  to  the  close  of  the  Ameri- 
can Revolution.    2  vols. 
Lectures  on  the  French  Revolu- 
tion.   With  Index.    2  vols. 

SOUTHEY.— See  Ccnvper,  Wesley,  and 
(Illustrated  Library)  Nelson. 

STURM'S    Morning    Communings 

with  God,  or  Devotional  Meditations  for 
Every  Day.  Trans,  by  W.  Johnstone,  M.A. 

SULLY.    Memoirs  of  the  Duke  of, 

Prime  Minister  to  Henry  the  Great.  With 
Notes  and  Historical  Introduction.  4  Por- 
traits.   4  vols. 

TAYLOR'S    (Bishop    Jeremy)    Holy 

Living  and  Dying,  with  Prayers,  contain- 
ing the  Whole  Duty  of  a  Christian  and  the 
parts  of  Devotion  fitted  to  all  Occasions. 
Portrait. 
TEN  BRINK—  See  Brink. 

THIERRY'S  Conquest  of  England  by 

the  Normans ;  its  Causes,  and  its  Conse- 
quences in  England  and  the  Continent. 
By  W.  Hazlitt.  With  short  Memoir.  2  Por. 
traits.     2  vols. 

ULRICI  (Dr.)— See  Sfiakespeare. 

VASARI.  Lives  of  the  most  Eminent 

Painters,  Sculptors,  and  Architects.  By 
Mrs.  J.  Foster,  with  selected  Notes.  Por- 
trait. 6  vols.,  Vol.  VI.  being  an  additional 
Volume  of  Notes  by  Dr.  J.  P.  Richter. 

VOLTAIRE'S  Tales.  Translated  by 
R.  B.  Boswell.  Vol.  I.,  containing  '  Ba- 
bouc,'  Memnon,  Candide,  L'Ingenu,  and 
other  Tales. 

WERNER'S  Templars  in  Cyprus. 
Trans,  by  E.  A.  M.  Lewis. 

WESLEY,  the  Life  of,  and  the  Rise 

and  Progress  of  Methodism.  By  Robert 
Southey.     Portrait.    $s. 

WHEATLEY.  A  Rational  Illustra- 
tion of  the  Book  of  Common  Prayer. 

YOUNG  (Arthur)  Travels  in  France. 

Edited  by  Miss  Betham  Edwards.  With 
a  Portrait. 


HISTORICAL  AND  PHILOSOPHICAL  LIBRARIES. 


HISTORICAL    LIBRARY. 

22  Volumes  at  $s.  each.     ($1.  10s.  per  set.) 


EVELYN'S  Diary  and  Correspond- 

dence,  with  the  Private  Correspondence  of 
Charles  I.  and  Sir  Edward  Nicholas,  and 
between  Sir  Edward  Hyde  (Earl  of  Claren- 
don) and  Sir  Richard  Browne.  Edited  from 
the  Original  MSS.  by  W.  Bray,  F.A.S. 
4  vols.  45  Engravings  (after  Vandyke, 
Lely,  Kneller,  and  Jamieson,  &c). 

N.B. — This  edition  contains  130  letters 
from  Evelyn  and  his  wife,  printed  by  per- 
mission, and  contained  in  no  other  edition. 

PEPYS'  Diary  and  Correspondence. 

With  Life  and  Notes,  by  Lord  Braybrooke. 
With  Appendix  containing  additional 
Letters  and  Index.  4  rols.,  with  31  En- 
gravings (after  Vandyke,  Sir  P.  Lely, 
Holbein,  Kneller,  &c). 

N.B. —This  is  a  reprint  of  Lord  Bray- 
brooke's  fourth  and  last  edition,  containing 
all  his  latest  notes  and  corrections,  the 
copyright  of  the  publishers. 


JESSE'S   Memoirs   of  the  Court  of 

England  under  the  Stuarts,  including  the 
Protectorate.  3  vols.  With  Index  and  42 
Portraits  (after  Vandyke,  Lely,  &c). 

Memoirs  of  the  Pretenders  and 

their  Adherents.    6  Portraits. 

NTJ GENT'S    (Lord)    Memorials    of 

Hampden,  his  Party  and  Times.  With 
Memoir.  12  Portraits  (after  Vandyke 
and  others). 

STRICKLAND'S  (Agnes)  Lives  of  the 
Queens  of  England  from  the  Norman 
Conquest.  From  authentic  Documents, 
public  and  private.     6  Portraits.     6  vols. 

Life  of  Mary  Queen    of  Scots. 

2  Portraits.     2  vols. 
Lives  of  the  Tudor  and  Stuart 

Princesses.    With  2  Portraits. 


PHILOSOPHICAL   LIBRARY. 

17  Vols,  at  5*.  each,  excepting  those  marked  otherwise.     (3/.  19s.  per  set.) 


BACON'S  Novum  Organum  and  Ad- 
vancement of  Learning.  With  Notes  by 
J.  Devey,  M.A. 

BAX.     A  Handbook  of  the  History 

of  Philosophy,  for  the  use  of  Students. 
By  E.  Belfort  Bax,  Editor  of  Kant's 
'  Prolegomena.' 
COMTE'S  Philosophy  of  the  Sciences. 
An  Exposition  of  the  Principles  of  the 
Cours  de  Philosophic  Positive.  By  G.  H. 
Lewes,  Author  of  '  The  Life  of  Goethe.' 

DRAPER  (Dr.  J.  W.)    A  History  of 

the    Intellectual   Development  of  Europe. 
2  vols. 
HEGEL'S  Philosophy  of  History.    By 
J.  Sibree,  M.A. 

KANT'S   Critique   of  Pure  Reason. 

By  J.  M.  D.  Meiklejohn. 
Prolegomena  and  Metaphysical 

Foundations  of  Natural  Science,  with  Bio- 
graphy and  Memoir  by  E.  Belfort  Bax. 
Portrait. 


LOGIC,  or  the  Science  of  Inference. 

A  Popular  Manual.     By  J.  Devey. 

MILLER  (Professor).  History  Philo- 
sophically Illustrated,  from  the  Fall  of  the 
Roman  Empire  to  the  French  Revolution. 
With  Memoir.     4  vols.     31.  6d.  each. 

SCHOPENHAUER  on  the  Fourfold 

Root  of  the  Principle  of  Sufficient  Reason, 
and  on  the  Will  in  Nature.  Trans,  from 
the  German. 

Essays.     Selected  and  Translated  by 

E.  Belfort  Bax. 

SPINOZA'S  Chief  Works.  Trans,  with 
Introduction  by  R.  H.  M.  Elwes.    2  vols. 

Vol.   I.— Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus 
— Political  Treatise. 

Vol.   II. —  Improvement  of  the  Under- 
standing— Ethics— Letters. 


IO 


BOHWS  LIBRARIES. 


THEOLOGICAL    LIBRARY. 

15  Vols,  at  $s.  each  {except  Ckillingworth,  y>.  6d.).     (3I.  13s.  6d.  per  set.\ 


ELEEK.     Introduction   to    the    Old 

Testament.  By  Friedrich  Bleek.  Trans, 
under  the  supervision  of  Rev.  E.  Venables, 
Residentiary  Canon  of  Lincoln.     2  vols. 


CHI  LLI N  G  WORTH'S 

Protestants.     3s.  6d. 


Religion    of 


EUSEBITJS.     Ecclesiastical   History 

of  Eusebius  Pamphilus,  Bishop  of  Caesarea. 
Trans,  by  Rev.  C.  F.  Cruse,  M.A.  With 
Notes,  Life,  and  Chronological  Tables. 

EVAGRIUS.    History  of  the  Church. 

— See  Theodoret. 

HARDWICK.  History  of  the  Articles 

of  Religion  ;  to  which  is  added  a  Series  of 
Documents  from  a.d.  1536  to  A.D.  1615. 
Ed.  by  Rev.  F.  Proctor. 

HENRY'S  (Matthew)  Exposition  of 

the  Book  of  Psalms.    Numerous  Woodcuts. 

PEARSON  (John,  D.D.)    Exposition 

of  the  Creed.  Edit,  by  E.  Walford,  M.A. 
With  Notes,  Analysis,  and  Indexes. 


1    PHILO-JUD^US,    Works    of.      The 

Contemporary  of  Josephus.  Trans.  bj> 
C.  D.  Yonge.     4  vols. 

PHILOSTORGIUS.    Ecclesiastical 

History  of. — See  Sozomen. 

SOCRATES'  Ecclesiastical  History. 

Comprising  a  History  of  the  Church  from 
Constantine,  a.d.  305,  to  the  38th  year  of 
Theodosius  II.  With  Short  Account  of 
the  Author,  and  selected  Notes. 

SOZOMEN'S  Ecclesiastical  History. 

a.d.  324-440.  With  Notes,  Prefatory  Re- 
marks by  Valesius,  and  Short  Memoir. 
Together  with  the  Ecclesiastical  His- 
tory of  Philostorgius,  as  epitomised  by 
Photius.  Trans,  by  Rev.  E.  Walford,  M.A. 
With  Notes  and  brief  Life. 

THEODORET  and  EVAGRIUS.  His- 
tories  of  the  Church  from  a.d.  332  to  the 
Death  of  Theodore  of  Mopsuestia,  a.d. 
427  ;  and  from  a.d.  431  to  a.d.  544.  With 
Memoirs. 

WIESELER'S  (Karl)  Chronological 

Synopsis  of  the  Four  Gospels.  Trans,  by 
Rev.  Canon  Venables. 


ANTIQUARIAN    LIBRARY. 

35  Vols,  at  $s.  each.     (8/.  l$s.  per  set.) 


ANGLO-SAXON   CHRONICLE.  —  See 

Bede. 
ASSER'S  Life  of  Alfred.— See  Six  O.  E. 

Chronicles. 
BEDE'S    (Venerable)    Ecclesiastical 

History  of  England.  Together  with  the 
Anglo-Saxon  Chronicle.  With  Notes, 
Short  Life,  Analysis,  and  Map.  Edit,  by 
J.  A.  Giles,  D.C.L. 

BOETHIUS'S  Consolation  of  Philo- 
sophy. King  Alfred's  Anglo-Saxon  Ver- 
sion of.  With  an  English  Translation  on 
opposite  pages,  Notes,  Introduction,  and 
Glossary,  by  Rev.  S.  Fox,  M.A.  To 
which  Is  added  the  Anglo-Saxon  Version  of 
the  Metres  of  Boethius,  with  a  free 
Translation  by  Martin  F.  Tupper,  D.C.L. 

BRAND'S  Popular  Antiquities  of 
England,  Scotland,  and  Ireland.  Illus- 
trating the  Origin  of  our  Vulgar  and  Pro- 
vincial Customs,  Ceremonies,  and  Super- 
stitions. By  Sir  Henry  Ellis,  K.H.,  F.R.S. 
Frontispiece.    3  vols. 


CHRONICLES    of  the    CRUSADES. 

Contemporary  Narratives  of  Richard  Coeur 
de  Lion,  by  Richard  of  Devizes  and  Geof- 
frey de  Vinsauf ;  and  of  the  Crusade  at 
Saint  Louis,  by  Lord  John  de  Joinville. 
With  Short  Notes.  Illuminated  Frontis- 
piece from  an  old  MS. 

DYER'S  (T.  F.  T.)    British  Popular 

Customs,  Present  and  Past.  An  Account 
of  the  various  Games  and  Customs  asso- 
ciated with  different  Days  of  the  Year  in 
the  British  Isles,  arranged  according  to  the 
Calendar.  By  the  Rev.  T.  F.  Thiselton 
Dyer,  M.A. 

EARLY  TRAVELS  IN  PALESTINE. 

Comprising  the  Narratives  of  Arculf, 
Willibald,  Bernard,  Ssewulf,  Sigurd,  Ben- 
jamin of  Tudela,  Sir  John  Maundeville, 
De  la  Brocquiere,  and  Maundrell ;  all  un- 
abridged. With  Introduction  and  Notes 
by  Thomas  Wright.     Map  of  Jerusalem. 


ANTIQUARIAN  LIBRARY. 


ii 


ELLIS  (G.)  Specimens  of  Early  En- 
glish Metrical  Romances,  relating  to 
Arthur,  Merlin,  Guy  of  Warwick,  Richard 
Cceur  de  Lion,  Charlemagne,  Roland,  &c. 
&c.  With  Historical  Introduction  by  J.  O. 
Halliwell,  F.R.S.  Illuminated  Frontis- 
piece from  an  old  MS. 

ETHELWERD,     Chronicle   of.  —  Set 

Six  O.  E.  Chronicles. 

FLORENCE     OF    "WORCESTER'S 

Chronicle,  with  the  Two  Continuations  : 
comprising  Annals  of  English  History 
from  the  Departure  of  the  Romans  to  the 
Reign  of  Edward  I.  Trans.,  with  Notes, 
by  Thomas  Forester,  M.A. 

GEOFFREY    OF    MONMOUTH. 

Chronicle  of. — See  Six  O.  E.  Chronicles. 

GESTA  ROMANORUM,  or  Enter- 
taining Moral  Stories  invented  by  the 
Monks.  Trans,  with  Notes  by  the  Rev. 
Charles  Swan.     Edit,  by  W.  Hooper,  M.A. 

GILD  AS.    Chronicle  of.— See  Six  O.  E. 

Chronicles. 

GIRALDUS  CAMBRENSIS'  Histori- 
cal Works.  Containing  Topography  of 
Ireland,  and  History  of  the  Conquest  of 
Ireland,  by  Th.  Forester,  M.A.  Itinerary 
through  Wales,  and  Description  of  Wales, 
by  Sir  R.  Colt  Hoare. 

HENRY  OF  HUNTINGDON'S  His- 
tory of  the  English,  from  the  Roman  In- 
vasion to  the  Accession  of  Henry  II. ; 
with  the  Acts  of  King  Stephen,  and  the 
Letter  to  Walter.  By  T.  Forester,  M.A. 
Frontispiece  from  an  old  MS. 

INGULPH'S  Chronicles  of  the  Abbey 

of  Croyland,  with  the  Continuation  by 
Peter  of  Rlois  and  others.  Trans,  with 
Notes  by  H.  T.  Riley,  B.A. 

KEIGHTLEY'S  (Thomas)  Fairy  My- 
thology, illustrative  of  the  Romance  and 
Superstition  of  Various  Countries.  Frontis- 
piece by  Cruikshank. 

LEPSIUS'S  Letters  from  Egypt, 
Ethiopia,  and  the  Peninsula  of  Sinai ;  to 
which  are  added,  Extracts  from  his 
Chronology  of  the  Egyptians,  with  refer- 
ence to  the  Exodus  of  the  Israelites.  By 
L.  and  J.  B.  Horner.  Maps  and  Coloured 
View  of  Mount  Barkal. 

MALLET'S  Northern  Antiquities,  or 

an  Historical  Account  of  the  Manners, 
Customs,  Religions,  and  Literature  of  the 
Ancient  Scandinavians.  Trans,  by  Bishop 
Percy.  With  Translation  of  the  Prose 
Edda,  and  Notes  by  J.  A.  Blackwell. 
Also  an  Abstract  of  the  '  Eyrbyggia  Saga  ' 
by  Sir  Walter  Scott.  With  Glossary 
and  Coloured  Frontispiece. 


MARCO  POLO'S  Travels;   with  Notes 
and   Introduction.      Edit,   by  T.   Wright. 

MATTHEW  PARIS'S  English  His 
tory,  from  1235  to  1273.  By  Rev.  J.  A. 
Giles,  D.C.L.  With  Frontispiece.  3  vols.— 
See  also  Roger  of  IVendover. 

MATTHEW    OF    WESTMINSTER'S 

Flowers  of  History,  especially  such  as  re- 
late to  the  affairs  of  Britain,  from  the  be- 
ginning of  the  World  to  a.d.  1307.  By 
C.  D.  Yonge.     2  vols. 

NENNIUS.      Chronicle    of.— See   Six 

O.  E.  Chronicles. 

ORDERICUS  VITALIS'  Ecclesiastical 

History  of  England  and  Normandy.  With 
Notes,  Introduction  of  Guizot,  and  the 
Critical  Notice  of  M.  Delille,  by  T. 
Forester,  M.A.  To  which  is  added  the 
Chronicle  of  St.  Evroult.  With  Gene- 
ral and  Chronological  Indexes.     4  vols. 

PAULI'S  (Dr.  R.)  Life  of  Alfred  the 

Great.  To  which  is  appended  Alfred's 
Anglo-Saxon  Version  of  OResius.  With 
literal  Translation  interpaged,  Notes,  and 
an  Anglo-Saxon  Grammar  and  Glossary, 
by  B.  Thorpe.     Frontispiece. 

RICHARD    OF    CIRENCESTER. 

Chronicle  of. — See  Six  O.  E.  Chronicles. 

ROGER  DE  HOVEDEN'S  Annals  ol 

English  History,  comprising  the  History 
of  England  and  of  other  Countries  of  Eu- 
rope from  a.d.  732  to  a.d.  1 201.  With 
Notes  by  H.  T.  Riley,  B.A.     2  vols. 

ROGER  OF  WENDOVER'S  Flowers 
of  History,  comprising  the  History  of 
England  from  the  Descent  of  the  Saxons  to 
A.D.  1235,  formerly  ascribed  to  Matthew 
Paris.  With  Notes  and  Index  by  J.  A. 
Giles,  D.C.L.     2  vols. 

SIX  OLD   ENGLISH  CHRONICLES  i 

viz.,  Asser's  Life  of  Alfred  and  the  Chroni- 
cles of  Ethel werd,  Gildas,  Nennius,  Geof- 
frey of  Monmouth,  and  Richard  of  Ciren- 
cester. Edit.,  with  Notes,  by  J.  A.  Giles, 
D.C.L.     Portrait  ot  Alfred. 

WILLIAM      OF     MALMESBURY'S 

Chronicle  of  the  Kings  of  England,  from 
the  Earliest  Period  to  King  Stephen.  By 
Rev.  J.  Sharpe.  With  Notes  by  J.  A. 
Giles,  D.C-L.     Frontispiece. 

YULE-TIDE    STORIES.      A   Collection 
of  Scandinavian  and  North-German  Popu- 
lar Tales  and  Traditions,  from  the  Swa 
Danish,  and  German.    Edit,  by  B.  Thorpe. 


12 


BOHN'S  LIBRARIES. 


ILLUSTRATED    LIBRARY. 

73  Vols,  at  $s.  each,  excepting  those  marked  otherwise. 


ALLEN'S   (Joseph,  R.N.)   Battles  of 

the  British  Navy.  Revised  edition,  with 
Indexes  of  Names  and  Events,  and  57  Por- 
traits and  Plans.     2  vols. 

ANDERSEN'S   Danish   Fairy  Tales. 

By  Caroline  Peachey.  With  Short  Life 
and  120  Wood  Engravings. 

ARIOSTO'S     Orlando     Furioso.     In 

English  Verse  by  W.  S.  Rose.  With  Notes 
and  Short  Memoir.  Portrait  after  Titian, 
and  24  Steel  Engravings.     2  vols. 

BECHSTEIN'S   Cage   and   Chamber 

Birds  :  their  Natural  History,  Habits,  &c. 
Together  with  Sweet's  British  War- 
blers.   43  Coloured  Plates  and  Woodcuts. 

BONOMI'S  Nineveh  and  its  Palaces. 

The  Discoveries  of  Botta  and  Layard 
applied  to  the  Elucidation  of  Holy  Writ. 
7  Plates  and  294  Woodcuts. 

BUTLER'S  Hudibras,  with  Variorum 
Notes  and  Biography.  Portrait  and  28 
Illustrations. 

CATTERMOLE'S  Evenings  at  Had- 

don  Hall.  Romantic  Tales  of  the  Olden 
Times.  With  24  Steel  Engravings  after 
Cattermole. 

CHINA,  Pictorial,  Descriptive,  and 

Historical,  with  some  account  of  Ava  and 
the  Burmese,  Siam,  and  Anam.  Map,  and 
nearly  100  Illustrations. 

CRACK'S  (G.  L.)  Pursuit   of  Know-    i 

ledge  under  Difficulties.  Illustrated  by 
Anecdotes  and  Memoirs.  Numerous  Wood- 
cut Portraits. 

CRUIKSHANK'S  Three  Courses  and 

a  Dessert ;  comprising  three  Sets  of  Tales, 
West  Country,  Irish,  and  Legal  ;  and  a 
Me'lange.  With  50  Illustrations  by  Cruik- 
shank. 

Punch  and  Judy.    The  Dialogue  of 

the  Puppet  Show ;  an  Account  of  its  Origin, 
&c.  24  Illustrations  and  Coloured  Plates 
by  Cruikshank. 

DANTE,  in  English  Verse,  by  I.  C.Wright, 
M.A.  With  Introduction  and  Memoir. 
Portrait  and  34  Steel  Engravings  after 
Flaxman. 


(19/.  /s.  6d.  per  set.) 

DIDRON'S   Christian   Iconography; 

a  History  of  Christian  Art  in  the  Middle 
ASes-  By  the  late  A.  N.  Didron.  Trans. 
°y  E.  J.  Millington,  and  completed,  with 
Additions  and  Appendices,  by  Margaret 
Stokes.  2  vols.  With  numerous  Illustrations. 

Vol.  I.  The  History  of  the  Nimbus,  the 
Aureole,  and  the  Glory;  Representations 
of  the  Persons  of  the  Trinity. 

Vol.  II.  The  Trinity;  Angels;  Devils; 
The  Soul ;  The  Christian  Scheme.  Appen- 
dices. 

DYER  (Dr.  T.  H.)  Pompeii :  its  Build- 
ings and  Antiquities.  An  Account  of  the 
City,  with  full  Description  of  the  Remains 
and  Recent  Excavations,  and  an  Itinerary 
for  Visitors.  By  T.  H.  Dyer,  LL.D. 
Nearly  300  Wood  Engravings,  Map,  and 
Plan.     ys.  6d. 

Rome:    History    of  the    City,   with 

Introduction  on  recent  Excavations.  8 
Engravings,  Frontispiece,  and  2  Maps. 

GIL    BLAS.     The   Adventures   of. 

From  the  French  of  Lesage  by  Smollett. 
24  Engravings  after  Smirke,  and  10  Etch- 
ings by  Cruikshank.     612  pages.     6s. 

GRIMM'S  Gammer  Grethel;  or,  Ger- 

man  Fairy  Tales  and  Popular  Stories, 
containing  42  Fairy  Tales.  By  Edgar 
Taylor.  Numerous  Woodcuts  after  Cruik- 
shank  and  Ludwig  Grimm.     3s.  6d. 

HOLBEIN'S    Dance    of    Death   and 

Bible  Cuts.  Upwards  of  150  Subjects,  en- 
graved in  facsimile,  with  Introduction  and 
Descriptions  by  the  late  Francis  Douce 
and  Dr.  Dibdin. 

INDIA,  Pictorial,   Descriptive,   and 

Historical,  from  the  Earliest  Times.  100 
Engravings  on  Wood  and  Map. 

JESSE'S  Anecdotes  of  Dogs.  With 
40  Woodcuts  after  Harvey,  Bewick,  and 
others ;  and  34  Steel  Engravings  after 
Cooper  and  Landseer. 


KING'S  (C.  W.)    Natural  History  of 

Precious    Stones    and    Metals.      Illustra- 
tions.    6s. 


ILLUSTRATED  LIBRARY. 


»3 


LODGE'S     Portraits    of   Illustrious 

Personages  of  Great  Britain,  with  Bio- 
graphical and  Historical  Memoirs.  240 
Portraits  engraved  on  Steel,  with  the 
respective  Biographies  unabridged.  Com- 
plete in  8  vols. 

LONGFELLOW'S    Poetical    Works, 

including  his  Translations  and  Notes.  24 
full-page  Woodcuts  by  Birket  Foster  and 
others,  and  a  Portrait. 

Without  the  Illustrations,  3s.  bd. 

Prose  Works.      With  16    full-page 

Woodcuts  by  Birket  Foster  and  others. 

LOUDON'S  (Mrs.)  Entertaining  Na- 
turalist. Popular  Descriptions,  Tales,  and 
Anecdotes,  of  more  than  500  Animals. 
Numerous  Woodcuts. 

MARRY AT'S  (Capt.,  R.N.)  Master- 
man  Ready  ;  or,  the  Wreck  of  the  Pacific. 
(Written  for  Young  People.)  With  93 
Woodcuts.     3s.  bd. 

Mission;    or,  Scenes  in  Africa. 

(Written  for  Young  People.)  Illustrated 
by  Gilbert  and  Dalziel.     3*.  6d. 

Pirate  and  Three  Gutters.  (Writ- 
ten for  Young  People.)  With  a  Memoir. 
8  Steel  Engravings  after  Clarkson  Stan- 
field,  R.A.     3s.  6d. 

Privateersman.    Adventures  by  Sea 

and  Land  One  Hundred  Years  Ago. 
(Written  for  Young  People.)  8  Steel  En- 
gravings.    3.J.  6d. 

Settlers  1"   Canada.    (Written  for 

Young  People  10  Engravings  by  Gilbert 
and  Dalziel.     3s.  id. 

Poor     Jack.      (Written     for     Young 

People.)  With  16  Illustrations  after  Clark- 
son  Stanfield,  R.A.     3s.  6d. 

Midshipman  Easy.  With  8  full- 
page  Illustrations.     Small  post  8vo.  3s.  6d. 

Peter  Simple.  With  8  full-page  Illus- 
trations.    Small  post  8vo.  3s.  6d. 

MAXWELL'S  Victories  of  Welling- 
ton and  the  British  Armies.  Frontispiece 
and  4  Portraits. 

MICHAEL  ANGELO  and  RAPHAEL, 

Their  Lives  and  Works.  By  Duppa  and 
Quatremere  de  Quincy.  Portraits  and 
Engravings,  including  the  Last  Judgment, 
and  Cartoons. 

MUDIE'S  History  of  Eritish  Birds. 
Revised  by  W.  C.  L.  Martin.  52  Figures  of 
Birds  and  7  coloured  Plates  of  Eggs. 
a  vols. 


NAVAL    and   MILITARY    HEROES 

of  Great  Britain  ;  a  Record  of  British 
Valour  on  every  Day  in  the  year,  from 
William  the  Conqueror  to  the  Battle  of 
Inkermann.  By  Major  Johns,  R.M.,  and 
Lieut.  P.  H.  Nicolas,  R.  M.  Indexes.  24 
Portraits  after  Holbein,  Reynolds,  &c.   6s. 

NICOLINTS  History  of  the  Jesuits  : 
their  Origin,  Progress,  Doctrines,  and  De- 
signs.    8  Portraits. 

PETRARCH'S    Sonnets,    Triumphs, 

and  other  Poems,  in  English  Verse.  With 
Life  by  Thomas  Campbell.  Portrait  and 
15  Steel  Engravings. 

PICKERING'S  History  of  the  Races 

of  Man,  and  their  Geographical  Distribu- 
tion ;  with  An  Analytical  Synopsis  op 
the  Natural  History  of  Man.  By  Dr. 
Hall.  Map  of  the  World  and  12  coloured 
Plates. 

PICTORIAL      HANDBOOK     OF 

Modern   Geography   on   a   Popular   Plan. 
Compiled  from  the  best  Authorities,  English 
and  Foreign,  by  H.  G.  Bohn.     150  Wood- 
cuts and  51  coloured  Maps. 
Without  tLc  Maps,  3s.  6d. 

POPE'S  Poetical  Works,  including 
Translations.  Edit.,  with  Notes,  by  R. 
Camithers.  2  vols.  With  numerous  Illus- 
trations. 

Homer's    Iliad,    with    Introduction 

and  Notes  by  Rev.  J.  S.  Watson,  M.A. 
With  Flaxman's  Designs. 

Homer's  Odyssey,  with  the  Battle 

of  Frogs  and  Mice,  Hymns,  &c,  by 
other  translators  including  Chapman.  In- 
troduction and  Notes  by  J.  S.  Watson, 
M.A.    With  Flaxman's  Designs. 

Life,   including  many  of  his   Letters. 

By  R.  Carruthers.  Numerous  Illustrations. 

POTTERY    AND    PORCELAIN,    and 

other  objects  of  Vertu.  Comprising  an 
Illustrated  Catalogue  of  the  Bernal  Col- 
lection, with  the  prices  and  names  of  the 
Possessors.  Also  an  Introductory  Lecture 
on  Pottery  and  Porcelain,  and  an  Engraved 
List  of  all  Marks  and  Monograms.  By 
H.  G.  Bohn.     Numerous  Woodcuts. 

With  coloured  Illustrations,  10$.  6d. 

PROUT'S  (Father)  Reliques.  Edited 
by  Rev.  F.  Mahony.  Copyright  edition, 
with  the  Author's  last  corrections  and 
additions.  21  Etchings  by  D.  Maclise. 
R.A.     Nearly  600  pages. 

RECREATIONS  IN  SHOOTING.  With 

some  Account  of  the  Game  found  in  the 
British  Isles,  and  Directionsfor  the  Manage- 
ment of  Dog  and  Gun.  By  '  Craven.'  6* 
Woodcuts  and  9  Steel  Engravings  after 
A.  Cooper,  R.A. 


14 


BOHN'S  LIBRARIES. 


RENKIE.  Insect  Architecture.  Re- 
vised by  Rev.  J.  G.  Wood,  M.A.  186 
Woodcuts. 

ROBINSON  CRUSOE.  With  Memoir  of 
Defoe,  12  Steel  Engravings  and  74  Wood- 
cuts after  Stothard  and  Harvey. 

Without  the  Engravings,  3s.  6d. 

ROME  IN  THE  NINETEENTH  CEN- 

tury,  An  Account  in  1817  of  the  Ruins  ~f 
the  Ancient  City,  and  Monuments  of  Modern 
Times.  By  C.  A.  Eaton.  34  Steel  En- 
gravings.    2  vols. 

SHARPE  (S.)    The  History  of  Egypt, 

from  the  Earliest  Times  till  the  Conquest 
by  the  Arabs,  a.d.  640.  2  Maps  and  up- 
wards of  400  Woodcuts.     2  vols. 

SOUTHEY'S  Life  of  Nelson.  With 
Additional  Notes,  Facsimiles  of  Nelson's 
Writing,  Portraits,  Plans,  and  50  Engrav- 
ings, after  Birket  Foster,  &c. 

STARLING'S  (Miss)  Noble  Deeds  of 

Women  ;  or,  Examples  of  Female  Courage, 
Fortitude,  and  Virtue.  With  14  Steel  Por- 
traits. 

STUART  and  REVETT'S  Antiquities 

of  Athens,  and  other  Monuments  of  Greece  ; 
with  Glossary  of  Terms  used  in  Grecian 
Architecture.  71  Steel  Plates  and  numerous 
Woodcuts. 

SWEET'S  British  Warblers,  is.— See 

Bechstein. 
TALES    OF    THE    GENII;    or,    the 

Delightful  Lessons  of  Horam,  the  Son  of 
Asmar.  Trans,  by  Sir  C.  Morrell.  Numer- 
ous Woodcuts. 


TASSO'S    Jerusalem    Delivered.    In 

English  Spenserian  Verse,  with  Life,  by 
J.  H.  Wiffen.  With  8  Engravings  and  24 
Woodcuts. 

WALKER'S  Manly  Exercises;  con- 
taining  Skating,  Riding,  Driving,  Hunting, 
Shooting,  Sailing,  Rowing,  Swimming,  &c. 
44  Engravings  and  numerous  Woodcuts. 

WALTON'S  Complete  Angler,  or  the 

Contemplative  Man's  Recreation,  by  Izaak 
Walton  and  Charles  Cotton.  With  Me- 
moirs and  Notes  by  E.  Jesse.  Also  an 
Account  of  Fishing  Stations,  Tackle,  &c, 
by  H.  G.  Bohn.  Portrait  and  203  Wood- 
cuts, and  26  Engravings  on  Steel. 

Lives  of  Donne,  Wotton,  Hooker, 

&c,  with  Notes.  A  New  Edition,  re- 
vised by  A.  H.  Bullen,  with  a  Memoir 
of  Izaak  Walton  by  William  Dowling.  6 
Portraits,   6   Autograph    Signatures,    &c. 

WELLINGTON,  Life  of.  From  the 
Materials  of  Maxwell.  18  Steel  En- 
gravings. 

Victories  Of.— See  Maxwell. 

WESTROPP  (H.  M.)  A  Handbook  of 

Archaeology,  Egyptian,  Greek,  Etruscan, 
Roman.  By  H.  M.  Westropp.  Numerous 
Illustrations. 

WHITE'S   Natural   History  of  Sel- 

bome,  with  Observations  on  various  Parts 
of  Nature,  and  the  Naturalists'  Calendar. 
Sir  W.  Jardine.  Edit.,  with  Notes  and 
Memoir,  by  E.  Jesse.  40  Portraits  and 
coloured  Plates. 


CLASSICAL   LIBRARY. 

Translations  from  the  Greek  and  Latin. 


103  Vols,  at  5-r.  each,  excepting  those  marked  otherwise. 


(25/.  y.  per  set.) 


ACHILLES  TATIUS.  —  See  Greek 
Romances. 

.ESCHYLUS,    The    Dramas    of.     In 

English  Verse  by  Anna  Swanwick.     4th 
edition. 

The  Tragedies  of.     In  Prose,  with 

Notes  and  Introduction,  by  T.  A.  Buckley, 
B.A.     Portrait.     3s.  6d. 

AMMIANUS  MARCELLINUS.  His- 
tory  of  Rome  during  the  Reigns  of  Con- 
stantius,  Julian,  Jovianus,Valentinian,  and 
Valens,  by  C.  D.  Yonge,  B.A.  Double 
volume,     js.  td. 


ANTONINUS     (M.     Aurelius),     The 

Thoughts  of.  Translated,  with  Notes. 
Biographical  Sketch,  and  Essay  on  the 
Philosophy,  by  George  Long,  M.A. 
js.  6d.  Fine  Paper  edition  on  hand-made 
paper.     6s. 

APOLLONIUS  RHODIUS.     '  The  Ar- 

gonautica.'  Translated  by  E.  P.Coleridge. 

APULEIUS,  The  Works  of.  Com- 
prising the  Golden  Ass,  God  of  Socrates, 
Florida,  and  Discourse  of  Magic,  &c. 
Frontispiece. 


CLASSICAL  LIBRARY. 


IS 


ARISTOPHANES'  Comedies.    Trans.,    I 
with  Notes  and  Extracts  from  Frere's  and 
other  Metrical  Versions,  by  W.  J.  Hickie. 
Portrait.     2  vols. 

ARISTOTLE'S  Nicomachean  Ethics. 

Trans.,  with  Notes,  Analytical  Introduc- 
tion, and  Questions  for  Students,  by  Ven. 
Archdn.  Browne. 

Politics  and  Economics.    Trans., 

with  Notes,  Analyses,  and  Index,  by  E. 
Walford,  M.A.,  and  an  Essay  and  Life  by 
Dr.  Gillies. 

-  Metaphysics.  Trans.,  with  Notes, 
Analysis,  and  Examination  Questions,  by 
Rev.  John  H.  M'Mahon,  M.A. 

History  of  Animals.  In  Ten  Books. 

Trans.,  with  Notes  and  Index,  by  R. 
Cresswell,  M.A. 

Organon ;  or,  Logical  Treatises,  and 

the  Introduction  of  Porphyry.  With  Notes, 
Analysis,  and  Introduction,  by  Rev.  O. 
F.  Owen,  M.A.     2  vols.    3s.  6d.  each. 

Rhetoric  and  Poetics.   Trans.,  with 

Hobbes'  Analysis,  Exam.  Questions,  and 
Notes,  by  T.  Buckley,  B.A.     Portrait. 

ATHENEUS.  The  Deipnosophists. 
Trans,  by  C.  D.  Yonge,  B.A.  With  an 
Appendix  of  Poetical  Fragments.     3  vols. 

ATLAS   of  Classical  Geography.    22 

large  Coloured  Maps.  With  a  complete 
Index.     Imp.  8vo.    7s.  td. 

BION.—See  Theocritus. 

C/ESAR.      Commentaries    on    the 

Gallic  and  Civil  Wars,  with  the  Supple- 
mentary Books  attributed  to  Hirtius,  in- 
cluding the  complete  Alexandrian,  African, 
and  Spanish  Wars.    Portrait. 

CATULLUS,  Tibullus,  and  the  Vigil 

of  Venus.  Trans,  with  Notes  and  Bio- 
graphical  Introduction.  To  which  are 
added,  Metrical  Versions  by  Lamb, 
Grainger,  and  others.     Frontispiece. 

CICERO'S  Orations.  Trans,  by  C.  D. 
Yonge,  B.A.    4  vols. 

On  Oratory  and  Orators.    With 

Letters  to  Quintus  and  Brutus.  Trans., 
with  Notes,  by  Rev.  J.  S.  Watson,  M.A. 

On  the  Nature  of  the  Gods,  Divi- 
nation, Fate,  Laws,  a  Republic,  Consul- 
ship.   Trans,  by  C.  D.  Yonge,  B.A. 

— —  Academics,  De  Finibus,  and  Tuscu- 
lan  Questions.  By  C.  D.  Yonge,  B.A. 
With  Sketch  of  the  Greek  Philosophers 
mentioned  by  Cicero. 


CICERO'S  Works Continued. 

Offices;    or,     Moral    Duties.      Catc- 

Major,  an  Essay  on  Old  Age ;  Laelius,  an 
Essay  on    Friendship ;    Scipio's    Dream; 
Paradoxes ;    Letter  to  Quintus  on  Magis 
trates.     Trans.,  with  Notes,  by  C.  R.  Ed- 
monds.    Portrait.     3?.  6d. 

DEMOSTHENES'  Orations.  Trans., 
with  Notes,  Arguments,  a  Chronological 
Abstract,  and  Appendices,  by  C.  Rann 
Kennedy.    5  vols.    (One,  3s.  6d  ;  four,  5S.> 

DICTIONARY  of  LATLN  and  GREEK 

Quotations  ;  including  Proverbs,  Maxims, 
Mottoes,  Law  Terms  and  Phrases.  With 
the  Quantities  marked,  and  English  Trans- 
lations. With  Index  Verborum(622  pages). 

Index  Verborum  to  the  above,  with  the 

Quantities  and  Accents  marked  (56  pages), 
limp  cloth,     is. 

DIOGENES  LAERTIUS.  Lives  and 
Opinions  of  the  Ancient  Philosophers. 
Trans.,  with  Notes,  by  C.  D.  Yonge,  B.A. 

EPICTETUS.      The    Discourses     of. 

With  the  Encheiridion  and  Fragments. 
With  Notes,  Life,  and  View  of  his  Philo- 
sophy, by  George  Long,  M.A. 

EURIPIDES.  Trans,  by  T.  A.  Buckley, 
B.A.     Portrait.     2  vols. 

GREEK  ANTHOLOGY.  In  English 
Prose  by  G.  Burges,  M.A.  With  Metrical 
Versions  by  Bland,  Merivale,  and  others. 

GREEK  ROMANCES  of  Heliodorus, 

Longus,  and  Achilles  Tatius ;  viz.,  The 
Adventures  of  Theagenes  and  Chariclea ; 
Amours  of  Daphnis  and  Chloe  ;  and  Loves 
of  Clitopho  and  Leucippe.  Trans.,  with 
Notes,  by  Rev.  R.  Smith,  M.A. 

HELIODORUS.—  See  Greek  Romances. 

HERODOTUS.  Literally  trans,  by  Rev. 
Henry  Cary,  M.A.     Portrait.     3.5.  td. 

HESIOD,    CALLIMACHUS,    and 

Theognis.  In  Prose,  with  Notes  and 
Biographical  Notices  by  Rev.  J.  Banks, 
M.A.  Together  with  the  Metrical  Ver- 
sions of  Hesiod,  by  Elton ;  Callimachus, 
by  Tytler ;  and  Theognis,  by  Frere. 

HOMER'S  Iliad.  In  English  Prose,  with 
Notes  by  T.  A.  Buckley,  B.A.     Portrait. 

Odyssey,     Hymns,     Epigrams,    and 

Battle  of  the  Frogs  and  Mice.  In  English 
Prose,  with  Notes  and  Memoir  by  T.  A. 
Buckley,  B.A. 

HORACE.  In  Prose  by  Smart,  with  Notes 
selected  by  T.  A.  Buckley,  B.A.  Por- 
trait.    3$.  6d. 

JULIAN  THE  EMPEROR.    Cent:, 
Gregory  Mazianzea's  Two  [nvectixes  and 
Libanus' Monody,  with  fulian'    I 
cal  Works.    By  the  Rev;  C.  W.  King,  M.A. 


i6 


BOHN'S  LIBRARIES. 


JUSTIN,    CORNELIUS  NEPOS,   and 

Eutropius.  Trans.,  with  Notes,  by  Rev. 
J.  S.  Watson,  M.A. 

JUVENAL,      PERSIUS,     SULPICIA, 

and  Lucilius.  In  Prose,  with  Notes, 
Chronological  Tables,  Arguments,  by  L. 
Evans,  M.A.  To  which  is  added  the  Me- 
trical Version  of  Juvenal  and  Persius  by 
Gifford.    Frontispiece. 

LIVY.    The  History  of  Rome.    Trans. 

by  Dr.  Spillan  and  others.   4  vols.    Portrait. 

LONGUS.  Daphnisand  Chloe.—  SecGreek 
Romances. 

LUCAN'S  Pharsalia.  In  Prose,  with 
Notes  by  H.  T.  Riley. 

LUCIAN'S  Dialogues  of  the  Gods, 

of  the  Sea  Gods,  and  of  the  Dead.  Trans, 
by  Howard  Williams,  M.A. 

LUCRETIUS.  In  Prose,  with  Notes  and 
Biographical  Introduction  by  Rev.  J.  S. 
Watson,  M.A.  To  which  is  added  the 
Metrical  Version  by  J.  M.  Good. 

MARTIAL'S  Epigrams,  complete.  In 
Prose,  with  Verse  Translations  selected 
from  English  Poets,  and  other  sources. 
Dble.  vol.  (670  pages).     7s.  6d. 

MOSCHUS.— See  TJuocritus. 

JVIB'S  Works,  complete.  In  Prose, 
with  Notes  and  Introduction.    3  vols. 

PAUSANIAS'  Description  of  Greece. 

Trans.,  with  Notes  and  Index,  by  Rev. 
A.  R.  Shilleto,  M.A.,  sometime  Scholar  of 
Trinity  College,  Cambridge.     2  vols. 

?HALARIS.    Bentley's  Dissertations 

upon  the  Epistles  of  Phalaris,  Themisto- 
cles,  Socrates,  Euripides,  and  the  Fables 
of  .fesop.  With  Introduction  and  Notes 
by  Prof.  W.  Wagner,  Ph.D. 

'INDAR.  In  Prose,  with  Introduction 
and  Notes  by  Dawson  W.  Turner.  To- 
gether with  the  Metrical  Version  by  Abra- 
ham Moore.     Portrait. 

?LATO'S  Works.  Trans,  by  Rev.  H. 
Cary,  H.  Davis,  and  G.  Burges.     6  vols. 

—  Dialogues.  A  Summary  and  Analysis 
of.  With  Analytical  Index  to  the  Greek 
text  of  modern  editions  and  to  the  above 
translations,  by  A.  Day,  LL.D. 

•LAUTUS'S  Comedies.  In  Prose,  with 
Notes  by  H.  T.  Riley,  B.A.     2  vols. 

'LINT'S  Natural  History.  Trans., 
with  Notes,  by  J.  Bostock,  M.D.,  F.R.S., 
and  H.  T.  Riley,  B.A.     6  vols. 

'LINY.     The   Letters   of  Pliny  the 

Younger.  Melmoth's  Translation,  revised, 
with  Notes  and  short  Life,  by  Rev.  F.  C. 
T.  Bosanquet,  M.A. 


PLUTARCH'S     Morals.      Theosophical 
Essays.    Trans,  by  Rev.  C.  W.  King,  M.A. 


Trans,    by   Rev. 


Ethical  Essays. 

A.  R.  Shilleto,  M.A. 

Lives.    See  page  7. 

PROPERTIUS,  The  Elegies  of.   With 

Notes,  translated  by  Rev.  P.  J.  F. 
Gantillon,  M.A.,  with  metrical  versions 
of  Select  Elegies  by  Nott  and  Elton. 
3s.  6d. 

QUINTILIAN'S  Institutes  of  Oratory. 
Trans.,  by  Rev.  J.  S.  Watson,  M.A. 
2  vols. 

SALLUST,  FLORUS,  and  VELLEIUS 

Paterculus.  Trans.,  with  Notes  and  Bio- 
graphical Notices,  by  J.  S.  Watson,  M.A. 

SENECA  DE  BENEFICIIS.  Trans- 
lated  by  Aubrey  Stewart,  M.A.     3*.  6d. 

SENECA'S  Minor  Essays.  Translated 
by  A.  Stewart,  M.A. 

SOPHOCLES.    The  Tragedies  of.    In 

Prose,  with  Notes,  Arguments,  and  Intro- 
duction.    Portrait. 

STRABO'S  Geography.  Trans.,  with 
Notes,  by  W.  Falconer,  M.A.,  and  H.  C. 
Hamilton.  Copious  Index,  giving  Ancient 
and  Modern  Names.     3  vols. 

SUETONIUS'   Lives   of  the    Twelve 

Caesars  and  Lives  of  the  Grammarians. 
The  Translation  of  Thomson,  revised,  with 
Notes,  by  T.  Forester. 

TACITUS.      The  Works   of.     Trans., 

with  Notes.     2  vols. 

TERENCE  and  PH3EDRUS.  In  Eng- 
lish Prose,  with  Notes  and  Arguments,  by 
H.  T.  Riley,  B.A.  To  which  is  added 
Smart's  Metrical  Version  of  Phaedrus. 
With  Frontispiece. 

THEOCRITUS,     BION,     MOSCHUS, 

and  Tyrtaeus.  In  Prose,  with  Notes  and 
Arguments,  by  Rev.  J.  Banks,  M.A.  To 
which  are  appended  the  Metrical  Ver- 
sions of  Chapman.   Portrait  of  Theocritus. 

THUCYDIDES.    The  Feloponnesian 

War.  Trans.,  with  Notes,  by  Rev.  H. 
Dale.     Portrait.     2  vols.     35-.  6a.  each. 

TYRTJEUS.— See  Theocritus. 

VIRGIL.  The  Works  of.  In  Prose, 
with  Notes  by  Davidson.  Revised,  with 
additional  Notes  and  Biographical  Notice, 
by  T.  A.  Buckley,  B.A.     Portrait.     3s.  6d. 

XENOPHON'S  Works.  Trans.,  with 
Notes,  by  J.  S.  Watson,  M.A.,  and  Rev. 
H.  Dale.     Portrait.     In  3  vols. 


COLLEGIATE  SERIES  AND  SCIENTIFIC  LIBRARY. 


17 


COLLEGIATE     SERIES. 

II   Vols,  at  $s.  each.     (2/.  1 5*.  per  set.) 


DANTE.  The  Inferno.  Prose  Trans., 
with  the  Text  of  the  Original  on  the  same 
page,  and  Explanatory  Notes,  by  John 
A.  Carlyle,  M.D.     Portrait. 

The  Purgatorio.    Prose  Trans.,  with 

the  Original  on  the  same  page,  and  Ex- 
planatory Notes,  by  W.  S.  Dugdale. 


(Notes  on  the 
Edited  by  the 


DOBREE'S  Adversaria. 
Greek  and  Latin  Classics.) 
late  Prof.  Wagner.     2  vols. 

DONALDSON  (Dr.)    The  Theatre  of 

the  Greeks.  With  Supplementary  Treatise 
on  the  Language,  Metres,  and  Prosody  of 
the  Greek  Dramatists.  Numerous  Illus- 
trations  and  3  Plans.  By  J.  W.  Donald- 
son, D.D. 

GOETHE'S  Faust.  Parti.  German  Text, 
with  Hayward's  Prose  Translation  and 
Notes.  Revised,  with  Introduction  and 
Bibliography,  by  Dr.  C.  A.  Buchheim.   $s. 

KEIGHTLEY'S  (Thomas)  Mythology 

of  Ancient  Greece  and  Italy.  Revised  by 
Dr.  Leonhard  Schmitz.     is  Plates. 


HERODOTUS,    Notes   on.     Original 

and  Selected  from  the  best  Commentators. 
By  D.  W.  Turner,  M.A.    Coloured  Map. 

Analysis  and  Snmmary  of,  with 

a  Synchronistical  Table  of  Events — Tables 
of  Weights,  Measures,  Money,  and  Dis- 
tances—  an  Outline  of  the  History  and 
Geography — and  the  Dates  completed  from 
Gaisford,  Baehr,  &c.     By  J.  T.  Wheeler. 

NEW  TESTAMENT  (The)  in  Greek. 

Griesbach's  Text,  with  the  Readings  of 
Mill  and  Scholz,  and  Parallel  References. 
Also  a  Critical  Introduction  and  Chrono- 
logical Tables.  Two  Fac-similes  of  Greek 
Manuscripts.     650  pages,     y.  6d. 

or  bound  up  with  a  Greek  and  English 

Lexicon  to  the  New  Testament  (250  pages 
additional,  making  in  all  goo).     5s. 

The  Lexicon  separately,  2s . 

THUCYDIDES.  An  Analysis  antf 
Summary  of.  With  Chronological  Table 
of  Events,  &c,  by  J.  T.  Wheeler. 


SCIENTIFIC    LIBRARY. 

4S  Vols,  at  $s.  each,  excepting  those  marked  otherwise.     (12/.  igs.  per  set.) 


AGASSIZ    and   GOULD.    Outline  of 

Comparative  Physiology.  Enlarged  by 
Dr.  Wright.  With  Index  and  300  Illus- 
trative Woodcuts. 

BOLLEY'S    Manual    of  Technical 

Analysis ;  a  Guide  for  the  Testing  and 
Valuation  of  the  various  Natural  and 
Artificial  Substances  employed  in  the  Arts 
and  Domestic  Economy,  founded  on  the 
work  of  Dr.  Bolley.  Edit,  by  Dr.  Paul. 
100  Woodcuts. 


BRIDGEWATER  TREATISES. 

Bell  (Sir  Charles)  on  the  Hand ; 

its  Mechanism  and  Vital  Endowments,  as 
evincing  Design.  Preceded  by  an  Account 
of  the  Author's  Discoveries  in  the  Nervous 
System  by  A.  Shaw.    Numerous  Woodcuts. 

—  Kirby  on   the  History,  Habits, 

and  Instincts  of  Animals.  With  Notes  by 
T.  Rymer  Jones.     100  Woodcuts.     2  vols. 

Buckland's  Geology  and  Miner- 
alogy. With  Additions  by  Prof.  Owen, 
Prof.  Phillips,  and  R.  Brown.  Memoir  of 
Buckland.  Portrait.  2  vols.  15*.  Vol.  I. 
Text.  Vol.  II.  90  large  plates  with  letter- 
press. 


BRIDGEWATER    TREATISES. 

Continued. 

—  Chalmers  on  the  Adaptation  of 

External  Nature  to  the  Moral  and  Intel- 
lectual Constitution  of  Man.  With  Memoir 
by  Rev.  Dr.  Cumming.     Portrait. 

—  Front's  Treatise  on  Chemistry) 

Meteorology,  and  the  Function  of  Diges- 
tion, with  reference  to  Natural  Theology. 
Edit,  by  Dr.  J.  W.  Griffith.     2  Maps. 

Roget's  Animal   and  Vegetable 

Physiology.  463  Woodcuts.  2  vols.  6s. 
each. 

Kidd  on  the  Adaptation  of  Ex- 
ternal Nature  to  the  Physical  Condition  of 
Man.     3 j.  6d. 

CARPENTER'S  (Dr.  W.  B.)  Zoology. 
A  Systematic  View  of  the  Structure,  Ha- 
bits, Instincts,  and  Uses  of  the  principal 
Families  of  the  Animal  Kingdom,  and  of 
the  chief  Forms  of  Fossil  Remains.  Re- 
vised by  W.  S.  Dallas,  F.L.S.  Numerous 
Woodcuts.    2  vols.    61 .  each. 

Mechanical  Philosophy,  Astro. 

nomy,  and  Horology.  A  Popular  E.\;  j- 
sition.     1S1  Woodcuts. 


i8 


BOHN'S  LIBRARIES. 


CARPENTER'S  "Works.— Continued. 

Vegetable  Physiology  and  Sys- 
tematic Botany.  A  complete  Introduction 
to  the  Knowledge  of  Plants.  Revised  by 
E.  Lankester,  M.D.,  &c.  Numerous 
Woodcuts.    6*. 

Animal  Physiology.  Revised  Edi- 
tion.   300  Woodcuts.    6s. 

CHEVREUL  on  Colour.  Containing 
the  Principles  of  Harmony  and  Contrast 
of  Colours,  and  their  Application  to  the 
Arts  ;  including  Painting,  Decoration, 
Tapestries,  Carpets,  Mosaics,  Glazing, 
Staining,  Calico  Printing,  Letterpress 
Printing,  Map  Colouring,  Dress,  Land- 
scape and  Flower  Gardening,  &c.  Trans, 
by  C.  Martel.     Several  Plates. 

With  an  additional  series  of  16  Plates 

in  Colours,  7s.  6d. 

ENNEMOSER'S    History   of  Magic. 

Trans,  by  W.  Howitt.  With  an  Appendix 
of  the  most  remarkable  and  best  authenti- 
cated Stories  of  Apparitions,  Dreams, 
Second  Sight,  Table-Turning,  and  Spirit- 
Rapping,  &c.    2  vols. 

HOGG'S  (Jabez)  Elements  of  Experi- 
mental and  Natural  Philosophy.  Being 
an  Easy  Introduction  to  the  Study  _  of 
Mechanics,  Pneumatics,  Hydrostatics, 
Hydraulics,  Acoustics,  Optics,  Caloric, 
Electricity,  Voltaism,  and  Magnetism. 
400  Woodcuts. 

HUMBOLDT'S  Cosmos ;   or,  Sketch 

of  a  Physical  Description  of  the  Universe. 
Trans,  by  E.  C.  Otte,  B.  H.  Paul,  and 
W.  S.  Dallas,  F.L.S.  Portrait.  5  vols. 
3 s.  6d.  each,  excepting  vol.  v.,  5*. 

Personal  Narrative  of  his  Travels 

in  America  during  the  years  1799-1804. 
Trans.,  with  Notes,  by  T.  Ross.     3  vols. 

—  Views  of  Nature ;  or,  Contem- 
plations of  the  Sublime  Phenomena  of 
Creation,  with  Scientific  Illustrations. 
Trans,  by  E.  C.  Otte. 

HUNT'S  (Robert)  Poetry  of  Science ; 

or,  Studies  of  the  Physical  Phenomena  of 
Nature.  By  Robert  Hunt,  Professor  at 
the  School  of  Mines. 

JOYCE'S     Scientific    Dialogues.     A 

Familiar  Introduction  to  the  Arts  and 
Sciences.  For  Schools  and  Young  People. 
Numerous  Woodcuts. 

JUKES-BROWNE'S  Student's  Hand- 
book of  Physical  Geology.  By  A.  J. 
Jukes-Browne,  of  the  Geological  Survey  of 
England.  With  numerous  Diagrams  and 
Illustrations,  6s. 


JUKES-BROWNE'S  Works.-G;/^. 

The    Student's     Handbook    of 

Historical  Geology.  By  A.  J.  Jukes- 
Brown,  B.A.,  F.G.S.,  of  the  Geological 
Survey  of  England  and  Wales.  With 
numerous  Diagrams  and  Illustrations.    6s. 

The    Building    of    the    British 

Islands.  A  Study  in  Geographical  Evolu- 
tion. By  A  J.  Jukes-Browne,  F.G.S. 
7s.  6d. 

KNIGHT'S   (Charles)   Knowledge  is 

Power.  A  Popular  Manual  of  Political 
Economy. 

LILLY.    Introduction  to  Astrology. 

With  a  Grammar  of  Astrology  and  Tables 
for  calculating  Nativities,  by  Zadkiel. 

MANTELL'S  (Dr.)  Geological  Ex- 
cursions through  the  Isle  of  Wight  and 
along  the  Dorset  Coast.  Numerous  Wood- 
cuts and  Geological  Map. 

Petrifactions  and  their  Teach- 
ings. Handbook  to  the  Organic  Remains 
in  the  British  Museum.  Numerous  Wood- 
cuts.    6s. 

Wonders    of    Geology;     or,    a 

Familiar  Exposition  of  Geological  Pheno- 
mena. A  coloured  Geological  Map  of 
England,  Plates,  and  200  Woodcuts.  2 
vols.  7s.  6d.  each. 

SCHOUW'S  Earth,  Plants,  and  Man. 

Popular  Pictures  of  Nature.  And  Ko- 
bell's  Sketches  from  the  Mineral  Kingdom. 
Trans,  by  A.  Henfrey,  F.R.S.  Coloured 
Map  of  the  Geography  of  Plants. 

SMITH'S  (Pye)  Geology  and  Scrip- 
ture ;  or,  the  Relation  between  the  Scriptures 
and  Geological  Science.     With  Memoir. 

STANLEY'S    Classified   Synopsis  of 

the  Principal  Painters  of  the  Dutch  and 
Flemish  Schools,  including  an  Account  of 
some  of  the  early  German  Masters.  By 
George  Stanley. 

STAUNTON'S    Chess    Works.  —  See 

page  21. 

STOCKHARDT'S     Experimental 

Chemistry.  A  Handbook  for  the  Study 
of  the  Science  by  simple  Experiments. 
Edit,  by  C.  W.  Heaton,  F.C.S.  Nu- 
merous Woodcuts. 

URE'S  (Dr.  A.)  Cotton  Manufacture 

of  Great  Britain,  systematically  investi- 
gated ;  with  an  Introductory  View  of  its 
Comparative  State  in  Foreign  Countries. 
Revised  by  P.  L.  Simmonds.  150  Illus- 
trations.    2  vols. 

-  Philosophy  of  Manufactures, 
or  an  Exposition  of  the  Scientific,  Moral, 
and  Commercial  Economy  of  the  Factory 
System  of  Great  Britain.  Revised  by 
P.  L.  Simmonds.  Numerous  Figures. 
800  pages.     7s.  6d. 


REFERENCE  LIBRARY. 


19 


ECONOMICS   AND    FINANCE. 

GELBART'S  History,  Principles,  and  Practice  of  Banking.    Revised  to  1S81  by 
A.  S.  Michie,  of  the  Royal  Bank  of  Scotland.     Portrait  of  Gilbart.     2  vols.     iof. 

RICARDO  on  the  Principles  of  Political  Economy  and  Taxation.    Edited 
by  E.  C.  K.  Gonntr,  M.A.,  Lecturer,  Unirersity  College,  Liverpool.     5s. 

SMITH   (Adam).     The    Wealth    of   Nations.     An  Inquiry  into  the   Nature  and 
Causes  of.     Edited  by  E.   Belfort  Bax.     2  vols.     7s. 


REFERENCE   LIBRARY. 

32  Volumes  at  Various  Prices.     (S/.  is.  per  set.) 


BLAIR'S     Chronological     Tables. 

Comprehending  the  Chronology  and  His- 
tory of  the  World,  from  the  Earliest  Times 
to  the  Russian  Treaty  of  Peace,  April  1856. 
By  J.  W.  Rosse.     800  pages,     iof. 

Index    of   Dates.     Comprehending 

the  principal  Facts  in  the  Chronology  and 
History  of  the  World,  from  the  Earliest  to 
the  Present,  alphabetically  arranged ;  being 
a  complete  Index  to  the  foregoing.  By 
J.  W.  Rosse.     2  toIs.  sx.  each. 

BOHN'S    Dictionary  of  Quotations 

from  the  English  Poets.  4th  and  cheaper 
Edition.     6s. 

BOND'S  Handy-book  of  Rules  and 

Tables  for  Verifying  Dates  with  the  Chris- 
tian Era.     4th  Edition.     5s. 

BUCHANAN'S  Dictionary  of  Science 

and  Technical  Terms  used  in  Philosophy, 
Literature,  Professions,  Commerce,  Arts, 
and  Trades.  By  W.  H.  Buchanan,  with 
Supplement.  Edited  by  Jas.  A.  Smith.  6s. 

CHRONICLES  OF  THE  TOMBS.     A 

Select  Collection  of  Epitaphs,  with  Essay 
on  Epitaphs  and  Observations  on  Sepul- 
chral Antiquities.  By  T.  J.  Pettigrew, 
F.R.S.,  F.S.A.     5*. 

CLARK'S    (Hugh)    Introduction    to 

Heraldry.  Revised  by  J.  R.  Planche.  5s. 
950  Illustrations. 

With  tht  Illustrations   coloured,   15*. 

COINS,  Manual  ot.—See  Humphreys. 

COOPER'S  Biographical  Dictionary. 

Containing  concise  notice*  of  upwards  of 
15,000  eminent  persons  of  all  ages  and 
countries.     2  vols.     51.  each. 

DATES,  Index  of. —See  Blah' 

DICTIONARY  of  Obsolete  and  Pro- 
vincial English.  Containing  Words  from 
English  Writers  previous  to  the  19th 
Century.  By  Thomas  Wright,  M.A. , 
F.S.A.,  &c.     2  vols.  5*.  each. 


EPIGRAMMATISTS  (The).  A  Selec- 
tion from  the  Epigrammatic  Literature  of 
Ancient,  Mediaeval,  and  Modern  Times. 
With  Introduction,  Notes,  Observations, 
Illustrations,  an  Appendix  on  Works  con- 
nected with  Epigrammatic  Literature, 
by  Rev.  H.  Dodd,  M.A.     6s. 

GAMES,  Handbook  of.  Edited  by 
Henry  G.  Bohn.  Numerous  Diagrams. 
5s.     (See  also  page  21.) 

HENFREY'S  Guide  to  English 
Coins.  Revised  Edition,  by  C.  F.  Keary 
M.A.,  F.S.A.  With  an  Historical  Intro: 
duction.     6s. 

HUMPHREYS'     Coin    Collectors' 

Manual.  An  Historical  Account  of  the 
Progress  of  Coinage  from  the  Earliest 
Time,  by  H.  N.  Humphreys.  140  Illus- 
trations.    2  vols.  $s.  each. 

LOWNDES1  Bibliographer's  Manual 

of  English  Literature.  Containing  an  Ac- 
count of  Rare  and  Curious  Books  pub- 
lished in  or  relating  to  Great  Britain  and 
Ireland,  from  the  Invention  of  Printing, 
with  Biographical  Notices  and  Prices, 
by  W.  T.  Lowndes.  Revised  Edition  by 
H.  G.  Bohn.  6  yoIs.  cloth,  5.?.  each,  or  in 
4  vols.,  half  morocco,  il.  is. 

MEDICrNE,  Handbook  of  Domestic, 

Popularly  Arranged.     By  Dr.  H.  Davies. 

700  pages.     5^. 

NOTED  NAMES  OF  FICTION. 
Dictionary  of.  Including  also  Familiar 
Pseudonyms,  Surnames  bestowed  on  Emi- 
nent Men,  &c.  By  W.  A.Wheeler,  M.A.  5J. 

POLITICAL     CYCLOPAEDIA.      A 

Dictionary  of  Political,  Constitutional, 
Statistical,  and  Forensic  Knowledge  ; 
forming  a  Work  of  Reference  on  subjects 
of  Civil  Administration,  Pelitical  Economy, 
Finance,  Commerce,  Laws,  and  Social 
Relations.     4  vols.  3*.  6d.  each. 


20 


BOHN'S  LIBRARIES. 


PROVERBS,  Handbook  of.  Con- 
taining an  entire  Republication  of  Ray's 
Collection,  with  Additions  from  Foreign 
Languages  and  Sayings,  Sentences, 
Maxims,  and  Phrases.     5*- 

A  Polyglot  of  Foreign.  Com- 
prising French,  Italian,  German,  Dutch, 
Spanish,  Portuguese,  and  Danish.  With 
English  Translations.     5*. 


SYNONYMS  and    ANTONYMS;    or, 

Kindred  Words  and  their  Opposites,  Col- 
lected and  Contrasted  by  Ven.  C.  J. 
Smith,  M.A.     5s. 

WRIGHT  (Th.)—  See  Dictionary. 


NOVELISTS'    LIBRARY. 

13  Volumes  at  3 s.  6d.  each,  excepting  those  marked  otherwise.    (2/.  $s.  6d.per  set.) 


BJORNSON'S  Arne  and  the  Fisher 

Lassie.     Translated  from  the  Norse  with 
an  Introduction  by  W.  H.  Low,  M.A. 

BURNEY'S  Evelina ;  or,  a  Young 
Lady's  Entrance  into  the  World.  By  F. 
Burney  (Mme.  D'Arblay).  With  Intro- 
duction and  Notes  by  A.  R.  Ellis,  Author 
of '  Sylvestra,'  &c. 


—    Cecilia.      With 
Notes  by  A.  R.  Ellis. 


Introduction 
2  vols. 


and 


DE    STALL.      Corinne   or    Italy. 

By   Madame    de    Stael.      Translated    by 
Emily  Baldwin  and  Paulina  Driver. 


EBERS'  Egyptian  Princess, 
by  Emma  Buchheim. 


Trans. 


FIELDING'S    Joseph    Andrews  and 

his  Friend  Mr.  Abraham  Adams.  With 
Roscoe's  Biography.  Cruikshank's  Illus- 
trations. 

Amelia.     Roscoe's  Edition,  revised. 

Cruikshank'  s  Illustrations.     $s. 

Hiatory  of  Tom  Jones,  a  Found- 

ling.  Roscoe's  Edition.  Cruikshank's 
Illustrations,     2  vols. 

GROSSI'S    Marco    Visconti.     Trans. 
by  A.  F.  D. 

MANZONI.     The   Betrothed: 
a    Translation    of    '  I     Promessi 
Numerous  Woodcuts.     1  vol.     5*. 

STOWE  (Mrs.  H.  B.)  Uncle 
Cabin  ;  or,  Life  among  the  Lowly, 
page  Illustrations. 


being 
Sposi.' 

Tom's 

8  full- 


ARTISTS'    LIBRARY. 

9  Volumes  at  Various  Prices.     (2/.  Ss.  6d.  per  set.) 


BELL  (Sir  Charles).     The  Anatomy 

and  Philosophy  of  Expression,  as  Con- 
nected with  the  Fine  Arts.  5$.  Illustrated. 

DEMMIN.      History   of  Arms   and 

Armour  from  the  Earliest  Period.  By 
Auguste  Demmin.  Trans,  by  C.  C. 
Black,  M.A.,  Assistant  Keeper,  S.  K. 
Museum.    1900  Illustrations.    7s.  6d. 

FAIRHOLT'S  Costnme  in  England. 

Third  Edition.     Enlarged  and  Revised  by 
the   Hon.   H.  A.   Dillon,   F.S.A.     With 
more  than  700  Engravings.     2   vols.   5*. 
each. 
Vol.  I.  History.    Vol.  II.  Glossary. 

FLAXMAN.    Lectures  on  Sculpture. 

With  Three  Addresses  to  the  R.A.  by  Sir 
R.  Westmacott,  R.A.,  and  Memoir  of 
Flaxman.     Portrait  and  53  Plates.     6s. 


HE  AT  ON 'S    Concise    History    of 

Painting.  New  Edition,  revised  by 
W.  Cosmo  Monkhouse.     5s. 

LECTURES    ON    PAINTING    by   the 

Royal  Academicians,  Barry,  Opie,  Fuseli. 
With  Introductory  Essay  and  Notes  by 
R.  Wornum.     Portrait  of  Fuseli.    5s. 

LEONARDO    DA   VTNCI'S    Treatise 

on  Painting.  Trans,  by  J.  F.  Rigaud,  R.A. 
With  a  Life  and  an  Account  of  his  Works 
by  J.  W.  Brown.    Numerous  Plates.    5s. 

PLANCHE'S    History    of    British 

Costume,  from  the  Earliest  Time  to  the 
10th  Century.  By  J.  R.  Pianche.  400 
Illustrations,     ss. 


■( 


21 


) 


LIBRARY    OF    SPORTS    AND    GAMES. 

14  Volumes  at  y.  6d.  and  $s.  each.     (2I.  \§s.  per  set.) 


BOHN'S     Handbooks     of     Athletic 

Sports.  With  numerous  Illustrations.  In 
S  vols.     3-y.  6d.  each. 

Vol.  I.— Cricket,  by  Hon.  and  Rev.  E. 
Lyttelton;  Lawn  Tennis,  by  H.  W.  W. 
Wilberforce ;  Tennis,  Rackets,  and  Fives, 
by  Julian  Marshall,  Major  Spens,  and  J.  A. 
Tail  ;  Golf,  by  W.  T.  Linskill ;  Hockey, 
by  F.  S.  Cresweil. 

Vol.  II. — Rowing  and  Sculling,  by  \V. 
B.  Woodgate  ;  Sailing,  by  E.  F.  Knight ; 
Swimming,  by  M.  and  J.  R.  Cobbett. 

Vol.  III.— Boxing,  by  R.  G.  Allanson- 
Winn  ;  Single  Stick  and  Sword  Exercise, 
by  R.  G.  Allanson-Winn  and  C.  Phillipps- 
Wolley  :  Wrestling,  by  Walter  Armstrong ; 
Fencing,  by  H.  A.  Colmore  Dunn. 

Vol.  IV.— Rugby  Football,  by  Harry 
Vassall  ;  Association  Football,  by  C.  W. 
Alcock ;  Baseball,  by  Newton  Crane  ; 
Rounders,  Field  Ball,  Bowls,  Quoits,  Curl- 
ing, Skittles,  &c,  by  J.  M.  Walker,  M.A., 
and  C.  C.  Mott. 

Vol.  V.— Cycling  and  Athletics,  by  H.  H. 
Griffin  ;  Skating,  by  Douglas  Adams. 

Vol.  VI. — Practical  Horsemanship,  in- 
cluding Riding  for  Ladies.  By  W.  A. 
Kerr,  V.C. 

Vol.  VII. — Driving,  and  Stable  Manage- 
ment.    By  W.  A.  Kerr,  V.C.    [Preparing. 

Vol.  VIII. — Gymnastics,  by  A.  F.  Jenkin; 
Clubs  and  Dumb-bells,  by  G.  T.  B.  Cobbett 
and  A.  F.  Jenkin.  [/»  the  press. 

BOHN'S  Handbooks  of  Games.  New 
Edition,  entirely  rewritten.  2  volumes. 
3s.  6d.  each. 

Vol.  I.  Table  Games. 
Contents  :  —  Billiards,  with  Pool,  Pyra- 
mids, and  Snooker,  by  Major-Gen.  A.  W. 
Drayson,    F.R.A.S.,   with    a   preface  by 
W.  J.  Peall— Bagatelle,  by  '  Berkeley  '— 


Chess,  by  R.  F.  Green — Draughts,  Back- 
gammon, Dominoes,  Solitaire,  Reversi, 
Go  Bang,  Rouge  et  noir,  Roulette,  E.O., 
Hazard,  Faro,  by  '  Berkeley.' 

Vol.  II.  Card  Games. 
Contents  :— Whist,  by  Dr.  William  Pole, 
F.R.S.,  Author  of  'The  Philosophy  of 
Whist,  &c.'— Solo  Whist,  by  R.  F.  Green  ; 
Piquet,  Ecarte,  Euchre,  Bozique,  and 
Cribbage,  by  '  Berkeley ; '  Poker,  Loo, 
Vingt-et-un,  Napoleon,  Newmarket,  Rouge 
et  Noir,  Pope  Joan,  Speculation,  &c.  &c, 
by  Baxter- Wray. 

CHESS  CONGRESS  of  1862.  A  col- 
lection of  the  games  played.  Edited  by 
J.  Lowenthal.     New  edition,  $s. 

MORPHY'S  Games  of  Chess,  being 

the  Matches  and  best  Games  played  by  the 
American  Champion,  with  explanatory  and 
analytical  Notes  by  J.  L5wenthal.  With 
short  Memoir  and  Portrait  of  Morphy.    5s. 

STAUNTON'S  Chess-Player's  Hand- 
book. A  Popular  and  Scientific  Intro- 
duction to  the  Game,  with  numerous  Dia- 
grams.    5s. 

Chess  Praxis.    A  Supplement  to  the 

Chess-player's  Handbook.  Containing  the 
most  important  modern  Improvements  in 
the  Openings  ;  Code  of  Chess  Laws  ;  and 
a  Selection  of  Morphy's  Games.  Annotated. 
636  pages.     Diagrams.     5s. 

Chess-Player's    Companion. 

Comprising  a  Treatise  on  Odds,  Collection 
of  Match  Games,  including  the  French 
Match  with  M.  St.  Amant,  and  a  Selection 
of  Original  Problems.  Diagrams  and  Co- 
loured Frontispiece.     $s. 

Chess     Tournament     of    1851. 

A  Collection  of  Games  played  at  this  cele- 
brated assemblage.  With  Introduction 
and  Notes.     Numerous  Diagrams.     5*. 


BOHN'S  CHEAP  SERIES. 

Price  is.  each. 

A  Series  of  Complete  Stories  or  Essays,  mostly  reprinted  from   Vols,  in 

Bohn's  Libraries,  and  neatly  bound  in  stiff  paper  cover,  with 

cnt  edges,  suitable  for  Raihvay  Reading. 


ASCHAM   (Roger).      Scholeniaster. 

By  Professor  Mayor. 

CARPENTER  (Dr.  W.  B.).  Physi- 
ology of  Temperance  and  Total  Abstinence. 

EMERSON.     England   and  English 

Characteristics.  Lectures  on  the  Race, 
Ability,  Manners,  Truth,  Character, 
Wealth,  Religion.  &c.  &c. 

Nature :  An  Essay.      To   which  are 

added  Orations,  Lectures,  and  Addresses. 

Representative  Men :  Seven  Lec- 
tures on  Plato,  Swedenborg,  Mon- 
taigne, Shakespeare,  Napoleon,  and 
Goethe. 

— ;-  Twenty  Essays  on  Various  Sub- 
jects. 

The  Conduct  of  Life. 

FRANKLIN  (Benjamin).  Autobio- 
graphy.    Edited  by  J.  Sparks. 

HAWTHORNE  (Nathaniel).  Twice- 
told  Tales.    Two  Vols. 

Snow  Image,  and  Other  Tales. 

Scarlet  Letter. 

House  with  the  Seven  Gables. 

Transformation  ;    or   the    Marble 

Fawn.     Two  Parts. 

HAZLITT  (W.).  Table-talk:  Essays 
on  Men  and  Manners.     Three  Parts. 

— —  Plain  Speaker  :  Opinions  on  Books, 
Men,  and  Things.     Three  Parts. 

— —  Lectures  on  the  English  Comic 
Writers. 

Lectures  on  the  English  Poets. 

— —  Lectures  on  the  Characters  of 

Shakespeare's  Plays. 

— -  Lectures  on   the  Literature  of 

the  Age  of  Elizabeth,  chiefly  Dramatic. 


IRVING    (Washington).      Lives    of 

Successors  of  Mohammed. 

Life  of  Goldsmith. 

Sketch-book. 

Tales  of  a  Traveller. 

Tour  on  the  Prairies. 

Conquests     of     Granada     and 

Spain.     Two  Parts. 

Life  and  Voyages  of  Columbus. 

Two  Parts. 

Companions  of  Columbus :  Their 

Voyages  and  Discoveries. 

— :  Adventures  of  Captain  Bonne- 
ville in  the  Rocky  Mountains  and  the  Far 
West. 

— -  Knickerbocker's  History  of  New 

York,  from  the  beginning  of  the  World  io 
the  End  of  the  Dutch  Dynasty. 

Tales  of  the  Alhambra. 

Conquest  of  Florida  under  Her- 
nando de  Soto. 

Abbotsford  &  Newstead  Abbey. 

Salmagundi  ;  or,  The  Whim-Whams 

and  Opinions  of  Launcelot  Langstaff 
Esq. 

Bracebridge  Hall;  or,  The  Hu- 
mourists. 

Astoria  ;  or,  Anecdotes  of  an  Enter- 
prise beyond  the  Rocky  Mountains. 

Wolfert's  Roost,  and  other  Tales. 

LAMB  (Charles).  Essays  of  Ella. 
With  a  Portrait. 

Last  Essays  of  Elia. 

Eliana.    With  Memoir. 

MARRYAT  (Captain).     Pirate  and 

the  Three   Cutters.     With  a  Memoir   of 
the  Author. 


Bohn's  Select  Library  of  Standard  Works. 

Price  is.  in  paper  covers,  and  i^.  6d.  in  cloth. 

r.  Bacon's  Essays.    With  Introduction  and  Notes. 

2.  LESSING'S  Laokoon.     Beasley's  Translation,  revised,  with  Intro- 

duction, Notes,  &c,  by  Edward  Bell,  M.A.     With  Frontispiece. 

3.  Dante's  Inferno.     Translated,  with  Notes,  by  Rev.  H.  F.  Cary. 

4.  Goethe's   Faust.     Part  I.     Translated,   with    Introduction,   by 

Anna  Swanwick. 

5.  Goethe's    Boyhood.     Being    Part    I.    of    the    Autobiography. 

Translated  by  J.  Oxenford. 

6.  Schiller's  Mary  Stuart  and  The  Maid  of  Orleans.  Trans- 

lated by  J.  Mellish  and  Anna  Swanwick. 

7.  The  Queen's  English.    By  the  late  Dean  Alford. 

8.  Life  and  Labours  of  the  late  Thomas  Brassey.     By  Sir 

A.  Helps,  K.C.B. 

9.  Plato's  Dialogues  :  The  Apology— Crito—Phaedo— Protagoras. 

With  Introductions. 

10.  Moliere's  Plays  :  The  Miser— Tartuffe— The  Shopkeeper  turned 

Gentleman.     Translated  by  C.  H.  Walt,  NLA.     With  brief  Memoir. 

11.  Goethe's  Reineke  Fox,  in  English  Hexameters.     By  A.  Rogers. 

12.  Oliver  Goldsmith's  Plays. 

13.  LESSING'S  PLAYS  :  Nathan  the  Wise— Minna  von  Barnhelm. 

14.  PLAUTUS'S  COMEDIES:  Trinummus  —  Menaechmi  —  Aulularia  — 

Captivi. 

15.  WATERLOO  Days.     By  C.  A.  Eaton.     With  Preface  and  Notes  by 

Edward  Bell. 

16.  Demosthenes — On    the    Crown.      Translated    by    C.    Rann 

Kennedy. 

17.  The  Vicar  of  Wakefield. 

18.  Oliver  Cromwell.     By  Dr.  Reinhold  Pauli. 

19.  The  Perfect  Life.     By  Dr.  Channing.     Edited  by  his  nephew, 

Rev.  W.  H.  Channing. 

20.  Ladies  in  Parliament,  Horace  at  Athens,  and  other  pieces, 

by  Sir  George  Otto  Trevelyan,  Bart. 

21.  Defoe's  The  Plague  in  London. 

22.  Irving's  Life  of  Mahomet. 

23.  Horace's  Odes,  by  various  hands.  [Out  of  Print. 

24.  Burke's   Essay  on  'The    Sublime  and   Beautiful.'     With 

Short  Memoir. 

25.  Hauff's  Caravan. 

26.  Sheridan's  Plays. 

27.  Dante's  Purgatorio.     Translated  by  Cary. 

28.  Harvey's  Treatise  on  the  Circulation  of  the  Blood 

29.  Cicero's  Friendship  and  Old  Age. 

30.  Dante's  Paradiso.     Translated  by  Cary. 

31.  Chronicle  of  Henry  VIII.     Translated  by  Major   M.  A.   S. 

Hume. 


WEBSTER'S    INTERNATIONAL   DICTIONARY. 


An  entirely  Neiu  Edition  of  Webster's  Dictionary,  thoroughly 
Revised,  considerably  Enlarged,  and  reset  in  Neiu  Type  front 
beginning  to  end. 

Demy  ^to.  2118  pages,  3500  illustrations. 

Prices:    Cloth,  £1  us.  6d. ;    half-calf,  £2  2s.;    half-russia,  £2  5s.; 
calf,  £2  8s.      Also  in  2  vols,  cloth,  £1  14s. 

In  addition  to  the  Dictionary  of  Words,  with  their  pronunciation,  ety- 
mology, alternative  spellings,  and  various  meanings,  illustrated  by  quotations 
and  numerous  woodcuts,  there  are  several  valuable  appendices,-  comprising  a 
Pronouncing  Gazetteer  of  the  World ;  Vocabularies  of  Scripture,  Greek,  Latin, 
and  English  Proper  Names  ;  a  Dictionary  of  the  noted  Names  of  Fiction ;  a 
Brief  History  of  the  English  Language  ;  a  Dictionary  of  Foreign  Quotations, 
Words,  Phrases,  Proverbs,  &c.  ;  a  Biographical  Dictionary  with  10,000 
Names,  &c. 

This  last  revision,  comprising  and  superseding  the  issues  of  1S47,  1S64, 
and  1880,  is  by  far  the  most  complete  that  the  Work  has  undergone  during 
the  sixty-two  years  that  it  has  been  before  the  public.  Every  page  has  been 
treated  as  if  the  book  were  now  published  for  the  first  time. 


SOME  PRESS  OPINIONS  ON  THE  NEW  EDITION. 

'  We  believe  that,  all  things  considered,  this  will  be  found  to  be  the  best 
existing  English  dictionary  in  one  volume.  We  do  not  know  of  any  work 
similar  in  size  and  price  which  can  approach  it  in  completeness  of  vocabulary, 
variety  of  information,  and  general  usefulness.' — Guardian. 

'  The  most  comprehensive  and  the  most  useful  of  its  kind." — National 
Observer. 

'A  magnificent  edition  of  Webster's  immortal  Dictionary.'  —  Daily 
Telegraph. 

'A  thoroughly  practical  and  useful  dictionary.' — Standard. 

'A  special  feature  of  the  present  book  is  the  lavish  use  of  engravings, 
which  at  once  illustrate  the  verbal  explanations  of  technical  and  scientific 
terms,  and  permit  them  to  remain  readably  brief.  It  may  be  enough  to  refer 
to  the  article  on  "  Cross."  By  the  use  of  the  little  numbered  diagrams  we  are 
spared  what  would  have  become  a  treatise,  and  not  a  very  clear  one.  .  .  . 
We  recommend  the  new  Webster  to  every  man  of  business,  every  father  of  a 
family,  every  teacher,  and  almost  every  student — to  everybody,  in  fact,  who  is 
likely  to  be  posed  at  an  unfamiliar  or  half-understood  word  or  phrase.' — 
St.  fames 's  Gazette. 

Prospectuses,  with  Specimen  Pages,  on  application. 


London  :  GEORGE  BELL  &  SONS,  York  Street,  Covent  Garden. 


0 


^-oiNG  DEPT.  APR    2  m 


B 

Aris to teles 

437 

The  Organon 

A5 

03^ 

v.l 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
CARDS  OR  SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 

UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO  LIBRARY