Skip to main content

Full text of "Plato or Protagoras? Being a critical examination of the Protagoras speech in the Theætetus with some remarks upon error"

See other formats


B 

386 

S3 

MAIN 


PLATO  OR  PROTAGORAS  ? 


PLATO  OK  PROTAGORAS  ? 


BY  THE  SAME  AUTHOR. 

RIDDLES  OF  THE  SPHINX.  A  Study  in 
the  Philosophy  of  Evolution.  London:  SWAN 
SONNENSCHEIN  &  Co.  1891.  Pp.  xxvii,  468.  Price 
10s.  6d. 

AXIOMS  AS  POSTULATES  in  PERSONAL 
IDEALISM.  Edited  by  HENRY  STURT. 
London:  MACMILLAN  &  Co.  1902.  Pp.  87. 
Price  10s.  net. 

HUMANISM:  Philosophical  Essays.  London: 
MACMILLAN  &  Co.  1903.  Pp.  xxvii,  297.  Price 
8s.  6d.  net. 

STUDIES  IN  HUMANISM.  London:  MAC- 
MILLAN &  Co.  1907.  Pp.  xvii,  492.  Price 
10s.  net. 


PLATO  OR  PROTAGORAS  ? 

BEING  A  CRITICAL  EXAMINATION 

OP  THE 

PROTAGOEAS  SPEECH  IN  THE  THEAETETUS 

WITH   SOME   REMARKS 

UPON   ERROR 


BY 


R  C.  S.  SCHILLER,  M.A.,  D.Sc. 

FELLOW   AND  SENIOR  TUTOR   OF  CORPUS  CHRIST!  COLLEGE,   OXFORD 


OXFORD 
B.  H.  BLACKWELL,  50-51  BKOAD  STREET 

LONDON 

SIMPKIN,  MARSHALL  &  CO. 
1908 

All  Rights  Reserved 
PRICE  ONE  SHILLING  NET 


'  . 

6 


PREFACE. 

IN  a  somewhat  shorter  form  this  Essay  was  read  to 
the  Oxford  Philological  Society  on  the  15th  Novem- 
ber, 1907,  and  there  had  the  benefit  of  valuable 
criticisms  from  Mr.  H.  P.  Richards,  Mr.  R.  R.  Marett 
and  others.  I  have  in  consequence  been  enabled  to 
realize  more  clearly  the  divergences  from  the  current 
theories  as  to  the  import  of  the  Thecetetm  to  which 
my  own  studies  had  conducted  me.  They  proved  to 
be  more  extensive  than  I  had  suspected,  and  to 
involve  some  interesting  and  novel  issues  both  of  a 
literary  and  of  a  philosophic  character.  It  seemed  a 
duty,  therefore,  to  render  my  conclusions  accessible 
to  the  learned  world,  to  which  the  problems  of 
Platonic  criticism  are  of  perennial  interest.  But 
though  my  primary  purpose  is  to  raise  a  literary 
question,  I  have-not  thought  it  either  right  or  pos- 
sible to  slur  over  the  philosophic  importance  of  my 
thesis.  For  the  philosophical  significance  of  the 
Thecetetus  has  been  very  strangely  misconstrued.  It 
contains  no  tenable  account  of  knowledge.  It  con- 
tains  no  refutation  of  Humanism.  It  refutes  nothing 
but  an  extreme,  and  probably  exaggerated  or  mis- 
apprehended, form  of  sensationalism.  Nothing  of  all 
this  has,  apparently,  been  perceived.  Nor,  again, 
has  what  it  does  contain  been  fully  recognized.  It 

718992 


:a£;j  6 

:a,  swiping  repudiation  of  the  senses  and 
the  feelings  as  contributories  to  the  growth  of  know- 
ledge. It  contains  a  renunciation  by  Platonic  logic 
of  the  duty  of  explaining  the  individual.  It  is  a 
glorious  monument  of  the  Weltflucht  to  which  Pure 
Thought  finds  itself  impelled  whenever  it  is  taken 
seriously.  And  its  very  patient  and  subtle  researches 
into  the  problem  of  knowledge  culminate  in  the 
frankest  and  sublimest  confession  of  failure  which 
adorns  the  annals  of  intellectualistic  literature. 
Whether  or  not,  therefore,  it  is  possible  to  exhume 
from  it  the  lost  teachings  of  Protagoras,  it  is  clear 
that  in  the  study  of  Plato's  great  dialogues,  and  par- 
ticularly of  the  ThewMus,  lies  the  master-key  to  the 
understanding  of  the  whole  intellectualistic  position 
in  philosophy. 

OXFORD,  December,  1907. 


THE  fifth  century  B.C.  was  not  only  politically,  but  also 
intellectually,  tEev"great'  age  of  Greece.  In  the  history  of 
thought  also  it  makes  an  epoch.  In  it  philosophic  man  for 
the  first  time  rouses  himself  from  a  nightmare  of  childish 
guessing  and  a  stupor  of  helpless  wonder  at  the  vast  uncom- 1 
prehended  and  uncontrolled  panorama  of  external  nature.  | 
For  the  first  time  he  consciously  realizes  that  he  is  the 
Spectator  of  it  all,  that  the  whole  world's  infinite  complexity 
exists  in  relation  to  him,  and  that  he  has  not  merely  an  eye 
to  see  but  also  a  mind  to  devise  and  a  hand  to  execute,  if  he 
but  has  a  spirit  to  dare,  that  if  he  will  but  strive  patiently 
and  resolutely  to  co-ordinate  his  powers,  he  may  aspire  to 
control  the  flux  and  to  divert  it  into  channels  conducive  to 
the  attainment  of  his  highest  ends.  To  the  truth  of  which 
man  caught  his  first  glimpse  then  he  has  never  since  grown 
wholly  blind  again,  though  its  vision  has  often  been  obscured 
by  the  intoxicants  and  opiates  to  the  use  of  which  his  weak- 
ness and  his  sufferings  have  degraded  him. 

This  first  outburst  of  Humanism,  moreover,  was  in  some 
respects  the  greaTest  of  the  humanistic  eras.  For  it  was  the 
freest  and  most  spontaneous  and  the  least  hampered  by  man- 
made  obstacles.  All  the  later  revivals  of  Humanism  have 
been  subsequent  to  the  institution  of  a  learned  caste  whose 
academic  spirit  is  always  largely  occupied  with  ritual  obser- 
vances for  giving  his  due  (and  not  infrequently  a  good  deal 
more)  to  the  Demon  of  Pedantry ;  and  so  they  have  had  to 
live  and  operate  in  and  upon  a  more  or  less  unfavourable 
atmosphere.  They  could  not  always  succeed  in  developing 
their  Humanism  to  the  full. 

The  Humanists  of  the  Benaissance,  for  example,  were 
doubtless  sincere  humanists  in  their  intentions.  They  tried 


8 

to  set  man's  spirit  free  from  the  crushing  armour  of  Scholastic 
learning,  which  had  immobilized  the  medieval  sage  quite  as 
effectively  as  his  defensive  mail  had  immobilized  the  medi- 
eval knight.  But  they  soon  fell  lamentably  short  of  their 
noble  design  and  of  the  proud  name  they  had  assumed.  TotaL. 
v  humanity  cannot  be  identified  with  any  one  of  its  functions, 
and  so  '  humaner  letters  '  are  neither  the  '  whole  duty  of  man  " 
nor  even  more  than  comparatively  humane.  In  Scotland 
1  humanity  '  was  academically  reduced  to  Latin.  Hence  an 
impartial  judge  might  soon  doubt  the  superiority  of  Human- 
ism over  the  Scholasticism  which  it  supplanted  in  this  very 
>  point  of  pedantry.  Pedantry  is  the  poverty  of  the  soul,  and 
V  like  poverty  it  is  always  with  us,  while  it  is  only  occasionally 
that  the  human  spirit  rises  in  revolt  ag  unst  the  dust-storms 
of  finely  comminuted  knowledge  with  which  it  buries  alive 
all  originality  and  force. 

Unfortunately  we  have  little  direct  knowledge  of  this 
earliest  Humanism.  Its  heroes  and  martyrs,  Protagoras 
and Socrates,  have  left  us  no  memorial.  It  is  true  thatTEy 
the  irony^ofliistory  the  spiritual  heritage  of  one  of  them  soon 
became  a  valuable  asset,  to  be  disputed  over  by  the  philosophic 
schools  of  the  fourth  century,  and  that  so  in  the  end  Socrates 
has  become  for  history  what  it  suited  the  interest  of  the 
strongest,  i.e.,  of  the  greatest  writer,  that  he  should  appear. 
Plato  has  made  our  '  Socrates  '  into  an  intellectualist  like  him- 
self. But  this  is  manifestly  one-sided.  The  teaching  of  the 
real  Socrates  must  have  been  such  as  to  inspire  not  only  Plato, 
but  also  Xenophon,  and  Aristippus,  and  Antisthenes.  He 
cannot,  therefore,  have  been  the  beau  Mai  of  intellectualistic 
idealism  Plato  makes  him  out  to  be.  In  his  general  attitude 
towards  life  he  probably  came  far  nearer  to  the  progressive 
types  of  his  own  age  than  a  careless  reader  would  infer  from 
Plato.  For  Plato  has  made  him  into  a  stalking  horse  in  his 
campaign  against  his  own  professional  rivals,  the  Sophists. 
\  The  historic  Socrates,  however,  probably  got  on  with  Sophists 
\  of  his  time  even  better  than  Plato  admits  in  the  Protagoras. 

This  interpretation    of   Socrates,    however,  is  inferential. 
For  from  his  own  mouth  we  have  not  one  authentic  word. ' 
Protagoras  was  more  careful  of  posterity.     He  wrote  a  book, 


but  owing  to  no  fault  of  his,  there  has  come  down  to  us  as 
certainly  authentic  nothing  but  two  short  sentences,  which 
pierce  through  the  veiling  mists  of  tradition  like  the  glittering 
summits  of  the  Wetterhorn.  What  was  the  line  of  thought 
which  led  up  to  them,  what  were  the  reasonings  by  which 
they  descended  into  the  souls  of  men,  we  can  only  dimly 
guess.  Unless  indeed  there  is  truth  in  the  claim  of  Plato 
that  he  had  conquered  these  virgin  peaks  and  left  us  a  trust- 
worthy description  of  this  perilous  ascent. 

It  is  this  claim  of  Plato's  that  I  propose  to  examine,  and 
more   specifically,  the  Protagoras   Speech  in  the   Thecetetus 
166-68.     The  conventional  view  of  this  speech,  which  I  pro- 
pose to  contest,  is~ftiaTTMs~"5sN -lit LhTjlTi Cke'illic  in  substance) 
as  in  form,  and  that  in  it  Plato  has  tried  either  to  represents 
current  developments  of  Protagoreanism  made  by  his  dis-  \ 
ciples  or  to  embody  his  own  reflections  on  the  problem  of  / 
putting  a   reasonable  interpretation  on  an  obscure  dictum,    < 
and  that  the  decision  between  these  alternatives  does  not 
greatly  matter,  because  in  either  case  the  Speech  is  com- 
pletely  refuted  in  the  sequel. 

But  three  weighty  reasons  may  be  given  for  rejecting  this 
view.  (1)  The  somewhat  tentative  language  Plato  uses  as  to  J 
the  authenticity  of  the  defence  undertaken  by  his  '  Socrates  ' 1 
has  of  course  to  be  taken  quite  literally  on  this  theory.  It  is 
taken  to  mean  that  Plato  felt  really  doubtful  as  to  whether 
Protagoras  would  have  accepted  the  developments  attributed 
to  him.  But  it  is  obviously  possible,  and  indeed  more  natural, 
to  understand  his  phrases  otherwise.  Why  should  not  Plato 
really  have  felt  doubtful  about  the  success  of  an  attempt  to 
reproduce  an  authentic  line  of  argument  and  have  known 
that  his  success  might  be  ^impugned  ?  (2)  It  is  simply  not 
true  that  the  argument  of  the  speech  is  refuted,  either  in  the 
Thecetetus  or  anywhere  else  in  Plato.  (3)_The  conventional 
view,  lastly,  will  be  found  to  involve  itself  in  insoTul 
culties  of  a  literary  kind.  A  close  examination  of  the  argu- 
ment will  show  that  if  Plato  be  supposed  to  be  the  real  author 
of  the  Speech,  he  has  regaled  us  with  the  fancies  of  a  man  of 
straw  but  told  us  nothing  about  the  argument  of  the  real 

'      1 165  E,  168  C,  169  E,  171  E. 


10 


Protagoras.  Is  it  not  curious  moreover  that  the  argument 
/  of  the  Speech  is  never  really  answered  ?  Either,  therefore, 
Plato  is  made  into  a  dishonest  controversialist  who  suppresses 
his  opponent's  case  and  substitutes  for  it  figments  of  his  own, 
or  into  so  incoherent  a  thinker  that  he  cannot  see  the  scope 
of  an  argument  he  has  himself  invented. 

The  alternative  theory  I  venture  to  suggest  will  be  found 
cast  ncTsucTi  slur  upon  the  moral  and  intellectual  character 
of  Plato.  It  credits  Plato  with  an  honest  desire  to  state  his 
opponent's  case  and  assumes  merely  that  he  has  not  fully 
grasped  an  ^alien  point  of  view  for  the  appreciation  of  which 
his  whole  type  of  mind  unfitted  him,  and  which  even  so  he 
has  grasped  much  better  than  the  generality  of  intellectualists 
have  done  down  to  the  present  day.  j  It  proceeds  therefore^ 
from  two  very  reasonable  presuppositions,  (1)  that  Plato  did 
/  know  the  authentic  doctrine  of  Protagoras,  an?^2)  that  lie 
c?  diS  not  know  it  perfectly!  As  to  the  reason,  we  may  please 
ourselves^  He  may  not  have  actually  possessed  the  sup- 
pressed book  of  Protagoras  on  '  Truth '  and  have  been  forced 
to  rely  on  incomplete  memories  of  its  contents.  Or  again 
he  may  have  felt  that  he  had  not  completely  made  it 
out. 

.e  reasonableness,  however,  of  these  presuppositions  will 
t  appear  from  an  analysis  of_the  ^Protagoras  '  Sj^eech^ar^d 
the  reply  to  it  as  it  stands  in  Plato.  The  conclusions  I  shall 
try  to  estabksh  are  (I)  that  the  Speech  is  intended  to  give, 
and  probably  to  a  large  extent  succeeds  in  giving,  the  authentic 
argumentation  by  which  Protagoras  defended  his  great  dis- 
covery of  the  relativity  of  the  object  of  knowledge  to  the 
subject  (so  far  as  Plato  understood  it),  because  (II),  if  it  is 
taken  to  be  a  figment  of  Plato's  the  great  absurdity  results, 
that  Plato  did  not  notice  that  he  was  refuting  himself,  and 
(III),  it  contains  internal  evidence  showing  that  Plato  never 
understood  it.  (IV)  It  yields,  therefore,  trustworthy  evidence 
for  the  reconstitution  of  the  actual  doctrine  of  the  historic 
Protagoras,  and  (V)  ihis  is  confirmed  by  the  fact  that  it 
actually  contains  the  solution  of  the  problem  with  which 
Plato  wrestles  vainly  in  the  same  dialogue,  that  of  Truth  and 

Error. 

1 


11 

It  is  further  clear  that  these  positions  are  not  unconnected. 
For  if  the  current  view  that  the  positions  taken  up  in  the 
Speech  are  disposed  of  in  the  progress  of  the  argument  can 
be  shown  to  be  untenable,  if  it  is  demonstrable  that  the  argu- 
ments of  the  Speech  are  neither  refuted  nor  even  correctly 
represented  in  the  sequel,  it  becomes  highly  probable  that 
Plato  has  not  understood  it  aright,  and  that  therefore  it  is 
not  reallv  of  his  own  invention. 


If  then  the  substance  of  the  Speech  is  not  Plato's,  whose 
is  it?  Burely  J^rotagoras's  claim  to  it  should  take  precedence  " 
over  any  other.  Attempts  have  been  made  to  attribute  its" 
arguments  to  Aristippus,  on  the  ground  that  his  is  probably 
the  philosophy  attacked  in  the  earlier  parts  of  the  Theatetus. 
But  if  our  conception  of  the  real  relation  of  Socrates  to  the 
thought  of  his  contemporaries  be  right,  the  humanistic  strain 
in  Aristippus  may  well  have  come  down  to  him  from  his  master 
Socrates,  on  whom  the  spirit  of  the  fifth  century  was  doubt- 
less operative,  though  Plato  has  done  his  utmost  to  erase 
all  trace  thereof  from  his  picture  of  their  common  master. 
Hence  an  agreement  between  the  doctrines  of  Protagoras 
and  Aristippus  is  in  no  wise  inexplicable,  nor  would  it  prove 
that  the  Speech  belonged  to  the  latter. 

As  for  the  invention  of  imaginary  Protagoreans  against 
whom  Plato  is  imagined  to  be  so  eager  to  contend  as  to  ignore 
their  master,  that  surely  is  too  desperate  an  expedient  to  be 
sanctioned  by  any  sane  principles  of  historical  criticism.  In 
some  cases,  as  in  palliating  the  clearly  deliberate  misrepre- 
sentation of  Plato  by  Aristotle,  such  an  expedient  may 
commend  itself  to  the  timidity  of  reconcilers  reluctant  to 
admit  that  one  great  thinker  may  fail  to  appreciate  another, 
though  in  this  case  we  know  at  least  that  there  was  a 
Platonic  School  on  which  to  impose  the  burden  Aristotle 
falsely  fastens  on  to  Plato,  and  though  even  then  the  hypo- 
thesis does  not  cover  all  the  facts.  But  in  general  a  master^ 
contends  with  masters  and  not  with  disciples.  Moreover, 


12 

there  is  no  clear  evidence  that  Protagoras  had  any  disciples.1 
His  appears  to  have  been  one  of  the  rare  (but  all  the  sadder) 
cases  in  which  persecution  (like  that  of  the  Japanese  Chris- 
tians in  the  seventeenth  century)  really  achieved  its  purpose. 
There  is  no  evidence  to  show  that  Protagoras's  book  survived 
the  Athenian  persecution.  The  one  copy  which,  it  is  reason- 
able to  suppose,  no  persecution  could  extort,  viz.,  Protagoras's 
own,  must  have  perished  with  him  when  the  ship  went  down 
on  which  he  was  fleeing  from  the  pious  wrath  of  the  Athen- 
ians and  the  fate  which  subsequently  befel  Socrates.  Hence 
it  is  no  wonder  that  nobody  seems  to  know  anything  about 
Protagoras's  book,  beyond  the  title  and  the  two  dicta,  except 
Plato,  and  that  all  the  later  references  to  it  are  plainly  based 
on  his  account.  And  it  is  remarkable  that  even  Plato  does 
not  seem  to  have  first-hand  verbatim  knowledge  of  it,  though 
we  shall  see  that  he  must  have  known  a  great  deal  more 
about  it  than  any  one  has  done  since. 


II. 

If  we  are  willin^  to  accept  the  Speech  as  ^enuine  Prota- 
goreanism,  we  are  enabled  to  fill  up  a  great  and  mysterious 
lacuna  in  our  knowledge.  As  at  present  advised  we  know 
nothing  about  the  context  of  the  Homo  Mensura  dictum.  But 
obviously  it  must  have  had  one,  or  rather  two,  one  psycho- 
logical, the  other  logic  ah  No  man  makes  a  great  discovery 
without  being  led  to  it  by  a  psychic  process.  No  man  venti- 
lates what  may  be  taken  as  a  giant  paradox,  without  trying 
to  make  it  plausible  and  palatable  to  his  audience.  Especi- 
ally if  he  is  a  professional  teacher,  i.e.,  a  man  who  has  lived 
all  his  life  under  a  consciousness  that  his  living  depends  on 
the  approval  of  this  same  audience. 

It  is  utterly  shallow,  th^rpfpre.  to  regard  Protagoras's 
dictum  as  an  irresponsible  freak  of  subjectivism.  Subjec- 
tivism from  its  nature  can  never  be  unreflective,  any  more 
than  pessimism.  Objectivisms  and  optimisms  always  are 

1  Theodorus  in  the  Thezetetus  is  represented  (1)  as  his  friend,  and  (2)  as 
no  philosopher  but  a  mathematician.  As  for  the  Antimoerus  of  the 
Protagoras  (315  A)  we  never  hear  of  him  again. 


13 

initially  unreflective,  and  frequently  remain  so  to  the  end. 
For  the  necessities  of  life  have  severely  schooled  us  to  begin 
by  turning  outward  the  eye  of  the  soul,  and  the  last  thing 
that  man  thinks  of,  the  last  thing  he  discovers,  is  himself. 

It  is  psychologically  certain,  therefore,  that  Protagoras 
must  have  ha'cl,  "ancl  must  MV&  Elated,  interpgt"^  fp^.sfmg 
Jor^  his  position.  J3nt  we  are  in  the  unsatisfactory  position 
of  knowing  only  his  conclusion,  and  neither  its  premisses 
nor  its  context,  and  no  interpretation  of  the  Thecetetus  can 
be  adequate  which  takes  no  account  ancl  has  no  explanation 
of  this  fact. 

Can -we  suppose  that  Plato  was  equally  unfortunate,  equally 
ignorant  of  the  context  and  grounds  of  Protagoras's  dictum  ? 
Only  if  we  suppose  that  he  neither  possessed,  nor  had  ever 
read,  Protagoras's  book  on  '  Truth  ' ;  nay,  that  he  had  never 
heard  it  discussed  by  those  who  had  read  it.  But  this  is  ex- 
tremely improbable.  It  igjindeed  just  possible  that  Plato, 
knew  no  more  than  we  do.  It  is  quite  possible  that  Athenian 
persecution  so  successfully  suppressed  the-book  that  no  copy 
escaped  to  be  perused  by  Plato.  Indeed  this  is  even  probable, 
under  the  very  peculiar  circumstances  of  the  catastrophe 
which  ended  the  career  of  Greece's  greatest  Sophist.  We  may 
infer  this  also  from  the  hesitations  and  apologies  with  which 
Plato  always  accompanies  his  account  of  Protagoras.  _  These 
become  intelligible  if  we  suppose  that  he  possessed  no  copy 
of  the  book  himself  and  was  not  in  a  position  to  cite  textu- 
aUy.  anything  but  the  two  admitted  dicta. 

But  it  is  incredible  that  Plato  should  not  have  been 
familiar  wTith  the  substance  of  the  book.  It  was  published, 
as  the  crown  and  outcome  of  the  long  career  of  the  most 
popular  teacher  of  the  day,  in  Athens,  Plato's  native  city,  in 
411  (or  412)  B.C.,  when  Plato  was  already  well  advanced  in 
his  teens.  If  he  was  then  already  interested  in  philosophy, 
he  must  surely  have  read  it,  or  at  least  have  heard  it  dis- 
cussed. Even  if  he  was  not,  he  must  have  been  the  con- 
temporary of  dozens  who  had  read  it  and  of  hundreds  who 
had  heard  it  discussed;  for  in  a  democracy,  which  cannot 
act  with  a  tyrant's  promptitude,  some  time  would  elapse 
before  the  indignation  of  the  orthodox  could  gather  force 


14 

enough  to  lead  to  its  denunciation  and  destruction,  and  the 
withdrawal  of  Protagoras  from  the  city.  Plato,  therefore, 
was  in  a  position  to  ascertain  the  real  arguments  of  Pro- 
tagoras with  great  exactitude.  For  it  is  improbable  that 
they  were  protected  from  reproduction  by  their  abstruse- 
ness.  Protagoras  was  not  a  recluse  like  Heraclitus,  but  a 
popular  lecturer.  His  arguments  cannot  have  been  too  subtle 
to  be  committed  to  memory. 

But  if  Plato  knew,  not  indeed  textually  but  in  substance, 
the  arguments  which  Protagoras  had  advanced  for  his  position, 
why  on  earth  should  he  suppress  them  ?  Why  should  he  not 
reproduce  in  his  polemic  such  of  them  at  least  as  he  thought 
he  could  answer  ?  Why  be  at  pains  to  invent  bogus  argu- 
ments on  behalf  of  Protagoras,  when  the  genuine  ones  were 
extant,  and  might  even  be  remembered  by  the  seniors  in  his 
own  audience?  Surely  it  would  have  been  neither  artistic, 
nor  honest,  nor  prudent,  to  attempt  more  than  to  re- word  in 
a  condensed  form  the  substance  of  the  genuine  argument. 
And  this  is  precisely  what  the  Thecetetus  indicates  through- 
out. The  remark  in  171  E,  which  is  the  chief  ground  for 
attributing  to  Plato  the  complete  fabrication  of  the  Protagoras 
Speech,  does  not  imply  more  than  this,  if  it  is  not  unfairly 
pressed. 

III. 

If  Plato  had  invented  the  Protagoras  Speech,  he  would 
surely  have  made  a  better  job  of  it  polemically.  He  would 
have  taken  care  not  to  put  into  the  mouth  of  his  '  Protagoras  ' 
anything  his  '  Socrates '  did  not  subsequently  refute.  If^ 
therefore,  there  can  be  found  in  the  Speech  arguments  which 
tjie  Theatetus  does  not  refute,  we  may  be  sure  that  they  were 
not  of  Plato's  invention.  And  if  Plato  thinks  he  has  refuted 
them  and  it  can  be  shown  that  he  is  wrong,  this  confidence 
will  be  strengthened ;  there  will  remain  no  reasonable  doubt 
but  that  he  has  tried  in  his  Speech  to  represent  a  real  op- 
ponent's actual  views,  that  he  has  failed  to  understand  him, 
and  therefore  failed  to  dispose  of  him,  as  he  supposes. 

An  unprejudiced  reading  of  the  Protagoras  Speech  will,  I 
believe,  bear  out  all  these  contentions. 


15 

The  Speech  falls  into  three  parts.  (1)  166  A— C,  (2)  166 
D— 1M7  D,  and  (3)  167  D— 168  B.  (1)  '  Protagoras '  begins 
with  a  protest  against  the  verbalism  of  the  'Socratic'  con- 
tentions that  have  preceded.  The  memory  of  a  perception 
must  not  be  lumped  together  with  the  perception.  It  is  in 
no  wise  absurd  that  the  same  person  should  know  and  not 
know  the  same  thing — at  least,  we  must  add,  if  as  in  Plato's 
examples  (165,  etc.)  the  thing  is  taken  in  a  different  reference. 
As  for  the  difficulty  of  the  change  in  the  knower  which 
results  from  his  interaction  with  the  object,  we  can,  if  you 
insist  that  he  cannot  be  identical  in  change,  regard  him  as 
an.  infinite  plurality-1  '  No',  says  Protagoras,  '  face  the  real 
point :  deny  outright  that  we  have  peculiar  and  individual 
perceptions,  which  we  alone  experience.' 

In  part  (2)  he  expounds  his  true  doctrine  and  refutes  the 
misinterpretations  put  upon  it.     '  While  I  affirm  that  each    */  3  £ 
man  is  the  measure  of  what  is  "  true  "  for  him,  I  do  not  deny 

f^^Sff^^^ 

that  one  man  may  be  10,000  times  as  good  as  an  o  trie"  r,  in  this 
very  point  of  what  appears  to  him  and  is  to  him  "true".  It^ 
is  thus  that  the  wise  man  is  distinguished  from  the  fool ;  he 
is  one  who  is  able,  when  things  appear  to  us  and  are  bad,  to 
make  them  appear  and  be  good.'  [I.e.,  who  teaches  us  how 
to  make  the  best  of  a  bad  job  and  to  adjust  ourselves  to  life.] 
1  Your  own  illustration  of  the  sick  man  to  whom  what  is  sweet 
to  the  healthy  seems  bitter  tells  against  you,  Socrates.  It  is 
futile  to  make  either  of  them  any  "wiser"  than  they  are,  or 
to  declare  that  the  sick  man  is  uninstructed  in  judging  as  he  / 
does  :  what  he  needs  is  to  be  altered ;  for  the  contrary  condi-  v 
tion  is  the  better.  Thus  the  sophist's  task  is  practical  like  the 
doctor's ;  but  his  ministrations  use  words,  instead  of  drugs, 
to  produce  a  better  state  of  mind.  There  is  no  question, 
therefore,  of  turning  "  false "  opinions  into  "true";  all  we 
opine  is  always  "  true "  in  so  far  as  it  expresses  what  we 
experience.  Lut  whereas  a  soul  in  bad  condition  opines 

1  Compare  with  this  James's  analysis  of  the  knower  into  a  succession 
of  momentary  I's,  each  inheriting  and  summing  up  his  predecessor.  Any 
dynamic  account  of  knowing  will  tend  to  have  recourse  to  such  descrip- 
tions, in  order  to  combat  the  useless  assumption  of  a  static  knower,  and 
will  be  similarly  charged  with  destroying  the  knower's  reality. 


16 

badly,  a  good  one  produces  good  thoughts.  Some  mistakenly 
call  such  "  better  "  appearances  "  truer,"  but  I  merely  "  better  " 
or  "  worse  "  but  not  "  truer  ".  Wise  men,  therefore,  are  they 
who,  like  the  physicians  of  bodies,  or  the  cultivators  of  plants, 
train  men  to  perceive  aright.  And  the  sage  or  *  sophist  ' 
performs  a  similar  service  also  for  cities  ;  wherefore  he  earns 
his  pay. 

'  (3)  We  see,  therefore,  that  in  a  sense,  though  no  one  can 
be  said  to  opine  falsely,  some  are  wiser  than  others.'  The 
;Speech  concludes  with  a  grave  admonition  to  '  Socrates '  to 
cease  from  arguing  disputatiously,  and  points  out  the  harm 
this  does  by  disgusting  people  with  philosophy,  and  the  perils 
of  arguing  from  the  current  usage  of  words  which  only  lead 
to  puzzles. 


& 


IV. 

-rm   — 

In  its  whole  tone  and  contents  this  Speech  seems  to  me 
xactly  what  we  should  expect  from  an  attempt  at  authentic 
reproduction.  The  anti-intellectualism,  the  emphasis  on  the 
practical  side,  the  defence  of  pay  for  intellectual  work,  the 
didactic  tone,  the  high  mogaLgeriousness  (which  Plato  attests 
also  in  the  Protagoras),  the  disgust  with  the  endless  and  often 
aimless  '  dialectics  '  of  the  Greek  boulevardier,  the  consciousness 
of  the  dangers  of  verbal  traps,  these  are  all  characteristics 
we  might  expect  to  find  in  the  veteran  teacher  whose  mission 
it  was  to  guide  the  education  of  a  democratic  age. 

Why  then  should  we  hesitate  to  attribute  to  him  also  what 
is  the  cardinal  point  of  his  defence,  viz.,  the  distinction  between 
the  formal  dairn^  to  Jruth  which  every  judgment  makes  and  its 
?  ThisTpomt  is  made  lucidly,  repeatedly  and  emphatically, 
and  iHny  paraphrase  has  brought  it  out  still  more,  the  reason 
is  merely  that,  thanks  to  Plato,  most  philosophers  have 
become  involved  in  so  dense  an  intellectualistic  bias  that 
anything  which  runs  counter  to  it  has  to  be  made  very  clear 

But  the  distinction  is  quite  clearly  in  the  Greek, 
is  also  quite  clearly  the  complete  answer  to  the  attacks 
on  the  humanism,  miscalled  the  '  subjectivism,'  of  Protagoras, 
and  the  solution  of  the  problem  of  a  common  truth.    It  explains 


17 


how  we  pass  from  individual    claims   to   social  values,  and 
attribute  To  them  an  objective  validity,     ^be  bricks  ont  of    .. 
which  the  temple  o^  Truth  is  built  are  the  individual  judg-  " 
ments  which  supply  the  material.    "Every  one  is  continually 
making  them.  ^BuTofthese  a  large  proportion  are  half-baked, 
or  broken,  or  of  the  wrong  shapes.      So  these  have  to  be  re- 
jected.     They  may  still  seem   to  their  makers  subjectively 

*  true,'  but  they  are  objectively   useless.     Whoever,  on  the 
other  hand,  has  the  skill  to  devise  a  form  of  brick  which  is 
useful  finds  hosts  of  imitators.     He  becomes  an  architectonic 
authority,  and  is  called  in  to  mould  or  re-mould  the  bricks  of 
others.     And  so  dominant  patterns  arise  which  prevail  and 
attain  an  objective  validity.     But  this  validity  is  the  reward 
of  value^  and  the  result   of   selections   based  on  experience. 
The  '  validity '  of  a  claim  to  truth   is  neither  logically  nor      > 
etymologically  other  than  its  'strength.      Tnere  is  no  need 

to  presuppose  any  inaccessible  supercelestial  archetype  which      & 
ratifies  and  sanctifies  by  a   suprasensible  communion,  the 
human  imitations  we  inexplicably  make.    Still  less  do  we  need 
any  deus  ex  ?nachina  supernatural ly  to  establish  by  his  fiat  any 
initial  ^commonness*  of trutEQ    We  do  not  even  need  any 

*  independent '  object  magically  authenticating  its  '  true  copy  ' 
in  our  thoughts.1     All  we^jieed  is  that  there  should  hg^ 
facto  differences  in  the  value,  and  therefore  in  the  subsequent 

validity,  of  different  people's  judgments.     And  of  these  we 
have,  of  course,  abundance. 

It  is  noticeable,  however,  that  Protagoras  is  represented  as 
declining  to  call  these  superior  values  *  truths '.  They  are. 
'  bej.ter  '  but  not  '  truer  '.  If  so,  he  did  not  yet  perceive  that 

1  Lest  I  should  hereabouts  be  unintelligently  charged  with  denying 

*  objective  reality'  altogether,   I  must  append  a  note  to  this  remark. 
The  only  sense  (out  of  many)  in  which  a  Humanist  theory  of  knowledge 
does  away  with   'independent  objects'  is  the  utterly  nugatory  one  in 
which  the  'object'  is  made  so  'independent'  as  to  transcend  human 
cognition  altogether  :  all  the  other  senses  of  '  objectivity,'  it  expounds  and 
explains,   each  in  its  proper  place.     It  is  most  unfortunate  that  both 

*  realists  '  and  '  absolute  idealists'  should  apparently  have  piqued  them- 
selves on,  quite  irrationally,   affirming  just  this  superfluous  absurdity, 
and  on  tying  all  the  legitimate  senses  of  '  objectivity  '  on  to  it.     Of.  my 
Studies  in  Humanism,  pp.  439,  461-62. 


. 
w    an^ 


\\ 

a  \    all  'truths  '  are  '  values,'  and  therefore  '  goods,'  even  though 
an  individual's  truths  are  good  and  satisfying  only  to  himr 
their  vame  is  verY  restricted,   because  their  currency 
r  sma^-     Nor  agam  can  ne  have  seen  that  the  same  ambig- 

\  uity  which  pervades  truth-values  pervades  also  all  the  rest. 
'^  ^  ,VMany  things  are  judged  'good,'  which  are  not  really  good, 
"""^just  as  they  are  judged  'true'  without  being  really  true. 
Everywhere  there  is  needed  a  bridge  of  validation  by  use  to 
cross  the  gap  between  claim  and  validity.  -  But  it  is  also 
possible  either  that  Plato  has  not  here  reproduced  the  full 
subtlety  of  Protagoras's  argument,  or  that  Protagoras  was 
hindered  from  expressing  himself  fully  only  by  the  poverty 
of  Greek  philosophic  language,  not  yet  enriched  by  the 
genius  of  Plato.  Anyhow,  the  difference  between  Protagorean 
and  modern  Humanism  concerns  only  a  subordinate  point 
of  terminology.1 

What  now,  we  may  proceed  to  inquire,  does  Plato  make  of 
this  important  philosophic  distinction  he  has  attributed  to 
Protagoras  ?  It  is  astounding  to  find  that  he  makes  nothing 
of  it  whatsoever.  He  treats  it  almost  as  badly  as  the  other 
three  un-Platonic  points  made  in  the  Protagoras  Speech,  (1) 
the  repudiation  of  intellectualism  and  of  the  doctrine  that 
badness  is  simply  ignorance  (166  E  —  167  A),  (2)  the  demand 
for  an  alteration  of  reality  by  practical  action  and  not  by  dialec- 
tics (166  D  and  168  A),  and  (3)  the  declaration  that  the  State 
*",  may  err  morally  like  the  individual,  and  may  need  the  services 
I  of  the  moral  expert  (168  B).  These  three  points  the  Platonic 
4  Socrates  '  totally  ignores  in  the  sequel. 

The  conception  of  truth-values  he  just  refers  to,  but  his 
reference  to  it  is  worse  than  none  at  all.  For  it  only  shows. 
that  Plato  had  no  conception  of  the  meaning  and  scope  of 
the  argument  he  had  just  stated.  In  169  D,  he  starts  again 
from  the  bare  dictum  as  if  the  Speech  had  done  nothing  to 
explain  its  real  meaning  nor  given  it  a  philosophic  context. 
And  the  reasons  '  Protagoras  '  had  given  for  the  dictum  are 
actually  treated  as  concessions  derogating  from  its  validity 
and  inconsistent  with  his  original  assertion  !  Nothing  could 

1  Cf.  Studies  in  Humanism,  p.  36. 


19 

be  more  unfair  and  unenlightened,  or  even  more  contrary  to 
the  very  wording  of  the  Speech.  For  in  the  Speech  '  Prota- 
goras '  emphatically  puts  his  doctrine  forward  as  his  very  own, 
and  distinguishes  it  from  the  laxer  use  of  popular  language, 
(167  B1).  And  well  he  might ;  for  it  is  the  vindication,  not 
only  of  his  whole  career  as  a  skilled  adviser  and  educator, 
but  of  the  liberty  which  he  concedes  to  every  one  to  hold  by 
his  own  experience.  Such, a  profound  misconstruction  seems, 
possible  only  in  one  who  was  reproducing  with  imperfect  -V 
success  an  argument  he  did  not  understand.  / 

There  follows  immediately  afterwards  a  still  more  extra- 


ordinary proof  of  the  discomfort  which  the  Protagorean 
mode  of  thought  had  occasioned  in  Plato's  mind.  For  in 
169  E,  it  is  suggested  that  as  Protagoras  is  not  present  to- 
confirmthe  '  concessions  '  made  on  his  behalf,  it  will  perhaps- 
be  better  to  restrict  the  discussion  to  his  own  words,  the  ^ 
original  dictum  ! 

By  this  master-stroke  of  dialectical  manipulation  the 
whole  defence  of  Protagoras  is  declared  invalid  and  set 
aside,  and  we  are  once  more  reduced  to  the  bare  dictum 
and  stripped  of  all  knowledge  of  what  it  really  meant  in  its  con- 
text. This  procedure  is  so  arbitrary  that  even  Plato's  literary 
art  cannot  quite  reconcile  his  readers  to  it.  But  on  our 
hypothesis  it  is  at  least  intelligible.  On  the  hypothesis  that 
Plato  has  concocted  the  Protagoras  Speech  it  becomes  utterly 
unthinkable.  For  how  can  one  believe  that,  after  propounding 
a  defence  of  Protagoras  which  was  at  least  novel  and  striking 
even  if  it  was  not  completely  adequate,  Plato  should  at  once 
have  dropped  it,  merely  because  he  suddenly  felt  a  consci- 
entious qualm  lest  Protagoras  himself  should  not  have  ap- 
proved  of  it  ?  Surely  whether  the  argument  of  the  Speech  * 
was  Protagoras's  or  Plato's,  once  it  was  stated,  it  should 
have  been  answered,  and  in  the  latter  case  at  least  it  could 
have  been  answered  :  the  presumption,  therefore,  is  that  Plato- 
dispensed  himself  from  this  duty  because  he  perceived  that  it 
surpassed  his  powers.  For  it  is  worth  noting  that  though 
the  Speech  is  evicted,  it  is  never  refuted.  Its  points  are 


^ 


a  or]  rives  TO.  <pavTa(rp.aTa  VTTO  direipias  d\Tj6f)  KaXoiKTiv   cy  o>  8f  j9f  X  T  i  a> 
ra  trtpa  T&V  er(p<0v,  d\r)  Q  c  <TTf  pa  de  ovdev. 


20 

almost  ostentatiously  ignored  henceforth,  but  no  attempt  is 
made  to  answer  any  one  of  them,  and  the  argument  becomes 
almost  farcical  in  its  unfairness.  The  logical  value,  there- 
fore, of  the  ensuing  argument  is  slight. 

For  example,  (1)  in  170  A  Socrates  insists  on  treating  the 
difference  between  the  authority  and  the  fool  as  merely  one 
in  knowledge,  despite  the  protest  in  167  A,  against  this  very 
trick  of  intellect ualism.  Protagoras  having  denied  that 
differences  in  truth-value  were  merely  intellectual,  Plato 
makes  a  point  of  reaffirming  his  intellectualist  analysis 
dogmatically  and  in  the  very  same  words.  The  protest  of 
the  Speech,  therefore,  has  been  wholly  vain. 
f  (2)  So,  too,  were  the  protest  against  relying  too  much  on 
popular  language  and  the  explanation  of  the  apparently  un- 
familiar assertion  that  all  always  judge  '  truly '.  For  as 
170  C  shows,  Plato  continues  to  base  his  objections  on  the 
current  use  of  the  words  '  true  '  and  '  false '. 

(3)  The  argument  in  170  D,  which  seems  a  clincher  to  Plato, 
is  almost  ludicrously  inconclusive  to  one  who  has  grasped 
the  manifest  meaning  of  the  Protagoras  Speech.  Itjs  in  no 
wise  absurd  that  an  opinion  (which  you  may  roughly  call 

he  same ')  should  be  '  true '  to  me  and  '  false  '  to  you  ;  nor 
that  one  man  should  be  right  and  10,000  wrong. 

For  $)  it  may  well  be  '  true '  to  a  lover  that  his  mistress 
is  the  most  beauteous  creature  in  the  world  ;  but  it  by  no 
means  follows  that  this  is  '  true '  to  the  rest  of  the  world,  nor 
is  it  even  desirable  that  it  should  be.  If  then  it  is  true  that 
there  is  a  peculiar  and  personal  side  to  every  piece  of  know- 
ledge, he  who  .-has  the  experience  alone  can  judge  of  its  value./ 
He  alone  feels  where  the  shoe  pinches  or  sees  the  subjective 
glow  which  transfigures  the  landscape,  fi)  Even  where  we 
feel  entitled  to  abstract  sufficiently  from  this  individuality  of 
concrete  experiences  to  speak  of  a  'common'  situation,  it 
may  be  perfectly  legitimate  for  different  minds  to  evaluate 
it  differently.  All  views  may  be  right  from  their  several 
standpoints,  and  they  generally  are  so  more  or  less.  ,  To 
deny  that  the  '  true  '  mode  of  attaining  the  Good  varies 
•according  to  the  circumstances  of  the  agent  is  both  intoler- 
ance and  ineptitude,  (c)  Athanasius  contra  mundum  and  the 


21 

fact  that  all  new  truth  necessarily  starts  in  a  minorit 


one,  should  moderate  our  reliance  on  numbers  as  a  test  of 
truth.  '  Universal  consensus  '  is  a  consequence  and  not  a 
cause  of  truth. 

(4)  It  is  in  vain,  therefore,  that  Plato  attempts  (in  170  E 
—171  C)  to  show  that  on  his  own  principles  Protagoras  must 

bow  to  the  verdict  of  the  majority  who  reject  his  dictum. 
Plato's  argument  here  is  completely  vitiated  by  the  '  ambiguity 
of  truth,'  l  and  as  it  completely  ignores  the  distinction  made 
by  the  Protagoras  Speech,  it  is  a  mere  ignoratio  elenchi.  For 
'  Protagoras  '  has  already  explained  how  on  his  theory 
scientific  authority  was  constituted.  He  could,  therefore, 
reply  —  'My  dictum  may  be  "true"  (claim)  for  me,  even 
though  it  is  not  "  true"  for  all  the  world  besides.  There  is 
no  contradiction  in  this,  for  we  are  different.  I  am  Protagoras  ; 
you.  to  put  it  mildly,  are  —  not  !  And  I  may  already  be  right, 
though  no  one  else  perceives  it  yet.  For  eventually  men  may 
come  to  see  that  my  view  is  really  "  better  ".  And  then  the 
validity  of  the  truth  I  now  claim  will  be  admitted.' 

(5)  In  171  E  —  172  C  Plato  propounds  a  restriction  of  the 
dictum's  "cTaTm^to  matters   of   sense-perception,  exempting 
matters  of  health  and  disease  from  its  sway,  and  he  identifies 
this  restricted  claim  with  the   position  of  the  Protagoras 
Speech. 

This  passage,  rj  r;/iet9  vTreypatyapev  ffoijOovvres  IIp(oTay6paf 
which  has  already  been  referred  to  (p.  14),  at  first  sight 
seems  direct  evidence  in  favour  of  the  view  that  the  Speech 
is  really  a  Platonic  invention,  and  if  this  were  the  only  or 
the  best  interpretation  of  the  remark,  it  would  be  almost 
fatal  to  the  contention  of  this  study.  But  in  point  of  fact, 
it  may  be  shown  that  it  is  only  part  of  Plato's  misconstruction 
of  the  Speech,  and  that  upon  examination  it  tells  strongly  in 
favour  of  the  view  that  the  Speech  is  genuinely  Protagorean 
and  has  been  utterly  misunderstood  by  Plato.  To  put  the 
matter  quite  bluntly,  it  is  not  true  that  the  Speech  said  what 
Plato's  '  Socrates  '  now  says  it  said-  Tile  discrepancies  between 
what  was  said  and  what  is  now  alleged  may  doubtless  look 

1  As  I  have  shown  in  Studies  in  Humanism,  pp.  146-46. 


22 

small,  but  they  are  not  insignificant ;  and  it  is  obvious  that 
nothing  very  glaring  could  be  expected.  For  if  Plato  had 
become  aware  of  any  considerable  divergence  between  the 
text  of  the  Speech  and  his  subsequent  version  of  it,  he  would 
have  modified  one  or  the  other. 

(a)  The  assertion  that  the  restriction  now  proposed  is  a 
•concession  to  common-sense  on  the  part  of  Protagoreanism 
is  merely  a  repetition  of  the  remark  in  169  D.     It  does  not 
become   more  plausible  thereby.     And  it  has  already  been 
-explained  how  profound  a  misconception  of  the  chief  distinc- 
tion made  in  the  Speech  is  implied  in  this  assertion. 

(b)  Nothing  is  said  in  the  Speech  about  a  division  of  terri- 
tories whereby  the  sphere  of  perception  would  be  left  to  the 
dictum,  while  that  of  good  and  evil,  and  of  health  and  disease 
would  be  assigned  to  the  control  of  authority.     The  conten- 

,  '  tion  of  the  Speech  was  that  of  judgments  equally  true  one 
)  might  be  better  than  another.  And  this  was  laid  down  uni- 
versally. Neither  subjectivity  nor  valuation  was  confined  to 
sense-perceptions,  thus  implicitly  giving  the  lie  to  Plato's 
attempt  to  fuse  the  humanism  of  Protagoras  with  the  sensa- 
tionalism of  his  day,  an  attempt  the  arbitrary  nature  of 
which  is  as  good  as  confessed  in  '  Socrates's '  remark  in 
152  C,  that  he  is  divulging  a  '  secret  doctrine '  to  an  astonished 
world.  No  restriction,  therefore,  of  the*  personal  implication 
in  all  knowing  to  the  sphere  of  mere  perception  can  for  a 
moment  be  entertained  by  any'  logical  Protagoreanism,  and 
this  implication  must  carry  the  universality  of  valuations 
with  it.  If  e.g.,  I  am  short-sighted  and  you  are  not,  your 
visual  perceptions  will  be  *  better  '  than  mine.  But  this  will 
not  make  them  '  true '  to  me.  The  fact  that  you  can  read 
print  at  a  distance  impossible  to  me,  does  not  enable  me  to 
do  so,  though  the  manifest  superiority  of  your  practical  ad- 
justments will  induce  me  to  admit  and  to  envy  the  superior- 
!ity  of  your  perceptions.  I  shall  continue  to  see  a  blur,  where 
you  see  clearly,  as  before.  It  would  seem,  therefore,  that  in 
attempting  to  apply  the  distinction  of  the  Speech,  Plato  has 
restricted  it  in  a  way  which  the  Speech  does  not  warrant  and 
the  facts  refute.  Surely  a  curious  fact  on  the  hypothesis  that 
he  was  himself  the  author  of  the  distinction  ! 


23 

(c)  Plato's  quotation  of  the  words  of  the  Speech  is  seriously 
inaccurate.     He  substitutes   'healthful'  and  *  diseased,'  for 
•'  better  '  and  '  worse  '.     But  in  the  Speech  these  were  merely 
illustrations  of  the  general  principle,  and  the  distinction  was 
not  restricted  to  them. 

(d)  The  argument  abqutjhe  cities  in  ITfl^A — B  is  both  inac- 
curate a_nd  absurd".     Nothing  was  said  in  the  Spee~cfr~arbout 
the  '  advantageous  ; '  the  terms  used  were  '  good  '  and  '  evil '. 
Moreover,  the  compromise  proposed  is  impossible,  as  Plato 
must   have   been   fully   aware.     You   cannot    allow    States 
to   judge   as   they   please   about    the   just   and    the    moral, 
if  they  are  to  be  controlled  by  a  perception  of  their  true 
•advantage.     For  their  ideas  about  justice  also  may  chance  to 
be  extremely  disadvantageous  to  them,  and  may  therefore 
require  to  be  altered.     The  *  Protagoras  '  of  the  Speech  had 
talked  no  such  nonsense:  he  had  very  sensibly  and  truly  re- 
marked that  the  opinions  of  States  about  the  just  might  have 
to   be    altered,    just    as  those   of   the   sick   man  about  the 
sweet. 

la  short,  Plato's  references  do  not  exactly  reproduce  either 
the  words  or  the  sense  of  the  '  Protagoras  '  Speech,  and  thereby 
prove  pretty  conclusively  that  he  was  not  the  real  author  of  its 
contentions.  For  those  who  insist' on  believing  that  he  was, 
his  whole  handling  of  the  Speech  must  seem  an  unfathomable 
mystery.  He  first  contrives  this  brilliant  Speech,  which  con- 
tains a  number  of  points,  new  and  unheard  of  in  all  Platonic 
philosophy,  together  with  one  distinction  of  capital  importance. 
And  then  he  goes  on  as  if  he  did  not  know  what  he  had  done, 
as  if  nothing  had  happened !  The  main  point  is  blankly 
ignored,  the  references  to  the  Speech  are  all  curiously  vague 
and  inexact,  and  the  whole  Speech  is  almost  at  once  set  aside 
as  possibly  inaccurate,  on  an  absurd  pretext  that  the  wording 
is  not  by  Protagoras.  If  this  was  the  way  in  which  he  was 
going  to  treat  it,  why  did  Plato  trouble  to  make  a  statement 
he  could  make  so  little  of?  The  Thecetetus  would  have  been 
gayer  and  more  forceful  without  a  long,  halting  and  impotent 
discussion  of  what  seems  a  half-understood  position.  Nothing 
but  external  compulsion  would  drive  an  expert  controversi- 
alist to  such  shifts.  But  may  not  such  compulsion  have  been 

* 


24 

forthcoming  from  the  expectations  of  his  older  readers,  who 
remembered  the  actual  reasonings  of  Protagoras  and  required 
of  Plato  an  attempt  to  meet  them  ? 

And  the  philosopher  must  urge  this  difficulty  still  more 
insistently  than  the  literary  critic.  The  The&tetus  contains 
•/a  position  of  immense  philosophic  importance,  whether  it 
originated  with  Protagoras  or  with  Plato.  It  is  never  dealt 
with.  Why  not?  And  is  not  the  philosopher  seriously 
concerned  to  estimate  how  much  it  detracts  from  the  se- 
curity of  Plato's  chosen  creed  to  have  left  a  hostile  strong- 
hold, however  weakly  garrisoned,  untaken,  nay  unassailed, 
in  his  rear  ? 

(6)  When  after  a  long  digression,  in  the  course  of  which 
Plato  emphasizes  the  hopeless  transcendence  of  the  truly 
real  and  valuable  with  the  utmost  acerbity,  the  argument  is- 
resumed  in  177  C,  Plato  first,   quite  superfluously,  proves 
what  the  Protagoras  of  the  Speech  had  long  ago  pointed  out,. 
viz.,  that  cities  often  do  not  know  their  own  advantage. 

(7)  InJL78_A  a  fresh  point  is  made.     Can  it  be  maintained 
that  each  man  is  the  measure  not  only  of  his  present  per- 
ception, but  also  of  the  future  ?     Will  that  be  exactly  as  he 
anticipates  ?     And  doe£  not  the  knowledge  of  the  advantage- 
ous depend  mainly  o^i  the  future  ? 

The  Platonic  '  Socrates '  appears  finally  to  rest  his  case  on 

this  point  and  on  the  argument  in  171  C  [our  No.  (4)  ],  by 

which  Protagoras  was  alleged  to  refute  himself.     In  reality, 

^however,  the  appeal  to  the  future  leads  to  a  triumphant  vin- 

/    dication  of  the  Humanist  interpretation.     For  how  does  the 

L.f uture  decide  between  two  rival  theories  of  truth ?     By  the 

/\ value  of  the  consequences   to   which   they   severally   lead. 

<       That  is  precisely  the  meaning  of  the  pragmatic  testing  of 

truth  by  its  consequences.     Whether  Protagoras  would  have 

replied  in  this  way  if  the  point  had  been  brought  to  his  notice, 

we  are  not,  of  course,  in  a  position  to  say  ;  but  enough  has 

probably  been  said  to  show   that  if  we  read  the  The&tetus 

critically  and  do  not  credulously  swallow  every  claim  Plato 

chooses  to  make  without  verifying  it,  there  can  be  no  question 

of  a  refutation  of  the  argument  of  the  Protagoras  Speech  by 

the  subsequent  criticism. 


25 


V. 

Plato  himself,  moreover,  was  a  better  judge  of  the  value  of 
his  argument  than  his  followers,  and  so  was  not  unaware  of 
the  incomplete  character  of  his  dialectical  victory  over  the 
bare  dictum  of  Protagoras.  He  realizes  plainly  that  in  order 
to  justify  his  rejection  of  it,  it  is  incumbent  on  him  to  devise  a 
tenable  theory  of  Error.  For  even  '  subjectivism  '  cannot  be 
refuted  by  more  scepticism,  and  even  a  rationalistic  theory 
of  knowledge  is  bound  to  discover  some  difference  between 
*  truth  '  and  '  error'.  This  implication  of  his  logical  position, 
was  not,  of  course,  a  thing  to  make  too  dangerously  prominent, 
but  it  is  clearly  the  meaning  of  the  remark  in  190  E,_that 
'  if  we  cannot  show  that  false  opinion  is  possible,  we  shall 
be  obliged  to  admit  many  absurd  things  '.  The  '  many  absurd 
things  '  are  the  Protagorean  view  of  Truth  as  it  has  been 
interpreted  by  Plato.  And  the  connexion  between  it  and  a 
failure  to  solve  the  problem  of  jError  is  this  :  if  the  possibility 
of  Error  cann.ot  be  evpla-inpri  ffr*»~>  ™™  ^  nr>  «"fQiQQ  npimrm  ' : 
and  if  there  can  be  no  '  false  opinion '  then  all  opinions  are 
true  ;  but  this  was  precisely  what  Protagoras  had  meant,  ac- 
cording to  Plato.  Hence  the  Platonic  inquiry  is  on  its  own 
showing  in  the  awkward  position  of  being  bound  to  discover  a 
tenable  theory  of  Error  in  order  to  save  itself  from  a  relapse 
into  a  Protagorean  '  subjectivism,'  which  it  has  itself  rashly 
declared  to  be  equivalent  to  an  abolition  of  all  truth. 

Nor  does  the  fact  that  the  Platonic  interpretation  of  Prota- 
goras is  wrong,  in  any  way  relieve  the  logical  pressure  upon 
Plato's  intellectualism  at  this  point.  For  as  an  ad  hominem 
refutation,  a  failure  to-devise  a  theory  of  Error  tells  against 
Plato's  theory  in  any  case.  Whether  or  not  Protagoras  had 
really  denied  the  possibility  of  Error,  Plato's  theory  of  know- 
ledge must  irremediably  collapse,  if  it  cannot  account  for  the 
existence  of  Error.  And,  unlike  many  modern  intellectual- 
ists,  who  seem  to  contemplate  with  equanimity  their  total 
failure  to  discriminate  between  truth  and  error  and  to  regard 
it  as  quite  an  unimportant  defect  in  a  theory  of  knowledge, 
Plato  saw  this  clearly. 

Hence  the  zeal  and  perseverance  with  which  the  inquiry 


26 

is  prosecuted.  Plato  is  battling  pro  aris  et  focis,  to  save 
the  central  fire  of  intellectualisin  from  extinction,  and  it  is 
probably  because  he  realized  this  as  none  of  his  successors 
have  done  after  him,  that  he  produced,  his  great  classical  dis- 
cussion of  the  problem,  which  is  distinguished  by  ingenuity 
and  ennobled,  though  not  saved,  by  the  frank  confession  of 
final  failure. 

That  this  failure  was  an  inevitable  outcome  of  Plato's  pre- 
suppositions is  the  next  point  for  us  to  understand.  We 
shall  in  understanding  this  understand  also  that  no  intel- 
lectualist  theory  of  Error  is  possible,  and  consequently  no 
really  adequate  intellectualist  theory  of  knowledge.  For  a 
theory  of  knowledge  which  cannot  explain  Error  cannot 
discriminate  it  from  Truth,  and  so  cannot  explain  that 
either. 

With  the  usual   naive  objectivism  of   ancient   metaphy- 
^   sicians,  Plato  starts  from  the  assumption  that  Error  is  some- 
/*  thing  objective  and  inherent  in  the  object  of  knowledge.     I.e., 
'     Plato  has  made  the  usual  abstraction  from  the  human  and 
personal  side  of  knowledge  and  assumed  that  this  can  have 
no  bearing  on  the  theory  of  logic.     If,  therefore,  this  assump- 
tion is  wrong,  we  can  at  once  account  for  the  failure  of  his 
efforts,  without  being  driven  into  the  scepticism,  in  which 
intellectualist  epistemologies  invariably  end. 

But  to  be  more  specific,  if  the  possibility  of  Error  is  de- 
pendent on  the  nature  of  the  object,  there  must  be  an  object 
of  error  as  well  as  an  object  of  knowledge,  and  the  error 
must  consist  in  our  taking  the  one  for  the  other,  or  getting 
the  one  when  we  want  the  other.  To  know  this,  however, 
we  must  necessarily  know  both.  We  must  know,  that  is,  the 
Jobject  of  error  as  such,  and  to  do  this  would  of  course  be  not 
jerror,  but  truth.  For  we  should  '  apprehend  it  as  it  is '.  Again, 
in  so  far  as  an  object  of  knowledge  is  involved  in  error  recog- 
nised as  such,  it  is  known  truly.  Error,  therefore,  always 
involves  the  contradiction  that  we  must  simultaneously  both 
know  and  not  know  in  the  same  cognitive  reference.  Thus 
a  theory  of  Error  is  unthinkable.  The  same  conclusion 
follows  if  we  start  from  any  formal  view  of  Truth.  For  we 
thereby  incapacitate  ourselves  for  distinguishing  between  a 


•27 

truth  and  a  claim  to  truth,  and  as  the  latter  may  be  wrong, 
error  becomes  a  kind  of  truth  and  we  are,  once  more,  unable 
to  distinguish  between  truth  and  error. 

Such  in  essence  is  the  impasse  to  which  all  Plato's  in- 
genious speculations  in  the  end  conducted  him.  He  could 
not  find  the  real  clue  to  the  maze,  because  of  his  initial  abstrac- 
tions. Having  abstracted  from  the  personal  maker  of  the 
judgment,  he  never  noticed  that  errors  do  not  exist  as  such 
until  they  are  found  out.  A  false  judgment  is  in  form  indis- 
tinguishable from  a  true  one,  a  self-contradictory  judgment 
being  unmeaning  as  expressed.  Hence  in  dealing  with  errors 
no  man  can  ever  be  simultaneously  in  a  condition  of  both 
knowing  and  not  knowing.  While  we  maintain  the  'error,' 
we  judge  it  to  be  'true  '  :  when  we  have  discovered  it  to  be 
an  '  error,'  we  no  longer  affirm  it.  As  critics  we  can  of  course 
perceive  errors  which  others  judge  to  be  true.  Indeed,  the 
'  errors'  that  trouble  us  are  generally  not  our  own,  but  those 
of  others,  which  they  affirm  and  we  deny.  But  when  the 
traditional  'logic,'  after  tabooing  all  systematic  reference  to 
the  psychological  context  of  its  subject-matter,  proceeds  to 
treat  of  Error  in  the  abstract,  it  declines  to  look  beyond  the 
fact  that  '  the  same  '  proposition  is  both  affirmed  and  denied, 
both  known  and  not  known.  I.e.,  it  has  abstracted  from  this 
difference  in  the  persons  who  affirm  and  reject  the  errone- 
ous judgment.  But  this  difference  is  essential,  because  it 
may  always  affect  and  dissolve  the  unity  of  what  has  been 
called  '  the  same  '.  Hence  '  logic  '  has  debarred  itself  from 
all  intelligible  treatment  of  the  question. 

The  second  point  to  be  grasped  is  that  the  seat  of  Error  is 
not  in  any  defective  configuration  of  the  '  object/  but  in  its 
relation  to  a  cognitive  purpose.  That  some  errors  consist  in 
the  affirmation  of  non-existent  objects  is  not  only  unimpor- 
tant, but  wholly  irrelevant.  It  is  irrelevant  because  it  in- 
volves a  confusion  of  an  ontological  with  a  logical  *  object '. 
'TheJogic.ai.  'object'  is  never  non-existent,  even  though  we 
may  be  discussing  Centaurs,  Chimaeras,  Absolutes,  intellect- 
ualistic  theories  of  knowledge  and  other  ontological  nonen- 
tities. But  all  errors  denote  the  defeat  of  a  cognitive  purpose. 
Hence  the  failure  of  a  purposive  thought  to  attain  the  aim 


28 

or  *  object '  which  would  have  satisfied  it,  can  never  be  treated 
in  abstraction  from  tne  personal  aspecFotJoiowmg.  ITcan- 
not  be  described  per  se  or  be  represented  in  merely  formal 
(and  therefore  verbal)  terms.  It  always  implies  a  relation  to 
something  beyond  the  two  ends  of  the  proposition.  It  is 
nothing  intrinsic  in  the  judgment,  it  is  never  to  be  judged 
as  a  purely  intellectual  thing. 

How,  on  the  other  hand,  does  this  problem  look  if  we 
approach  it  from  the  aspect  of  knowledge  for  the  first  time 
seen  and  emphasized  by  Pjotagoras?  .  It  will  be  found  that 
this  much-maligned  and  little  understood  theory  has  no 
difficulty  in  coping  with  it.  For  it  starts  with  human 
knowing,  not  with  '  ideals '  of  a  '  perfect '  knowledge  inac- 
cessible to  man.  Every  judgment  is  a  claim  to  'truth,'  i.e., 
an  experiment  with  '  reality  '  as  it  appears  to  us.  But  such 
experiments  may  fail  as  well  as  prosper.  If  they  succeed, 
we  recognize  their  value  and  hail  them  '  true '.  If  they  fail,, 
wholly  or  in  part,  we  condemn  as  '  false,'  and  admitting  that 
we  were  '  wrong,'  withdraw  the  values  claimed.  Gradually 
in  the  course  of  time  ther;j,  are  thus  segregated  two  great 
realms,  of  light  and  darkness,  Truth  and  Error.  But  between 
the  two  will  lie  much  disputed  territory,  where,  either  because 
our  experience  is  not  yet  adequate  or  because  our  experi- 
ments have  not  been  decisive,  there  is  ample  room  for 
doubt  and  difference  of  opinion. 

But  only  a  mind  thoroughly  corrupted  with  dialectic  and 
corroded  with  scepticism  will  base  on  its  existence  a  charge- 
that  to  recognize  these  facts  is  to  abolish  the  conception  of 
Truth.  In  reality  we  are  here  on  the  holy  ground  where,, 
by  the  continuous  revision  of  values  and  the  rejection  of 
'errors,'  Truth  is  made,  where  knowledge  is  alive  and  grow- 
ing. And  the  fertile  soil  yields  the  only  sort  of  truth  that 
has  use  or  meaning  for  man.  You  cannot,  it  is  true,  raise 
on  it  any  humanly  fruitless  and  unprofitable  crop  of  Platonic 
Ideas.  If  the  seeds  of  such  sterilities  are  scattered  on  the 
ground  by  breezes  that  issue  from  the  bags  of  ^Eolus,  they 
will  fail  to  germinate  in  a  soil  so  richly  manured  by  the 
heart's-blood  of  human  desire  and  the  bones  of  the  martyrs 
of  human  science.  But  our  loss  is  nil ;  for  such  static  forms- 


29 

would  be  utterly  unsuited  to  our  needs.  We  need  plastic 
conceptions  that  can  adjust  themselves  to  the  dynamic  nature 
of  reality,  and,  in  Plato's  parlance,  can  know  the  'flux.'  It 
is  only  in  unmeaning  tautologies  that  the  '  ideas '  remain 
immobile  even  in  the  single  judgment.  In  all  real  knowing 
subject  and  predicate  always  have  their  meaning  changed  by 
being  combined  in  a  judgment,  alike  whether  this  growth 
enriches  only  the  mind  of  a  single  knower  or  extends  to  all 
those  who  are  interested  in  the  advancement  of  human 
knowledge.  All  .our  concepts,  therefore,  as  James  says,  are 
teleological  weapons  of  the  human  mind. 

Plato,  doubtless,  would  never  have  admitted  that  such  mere 
instruments  of  human  knowing  were  true  '  Ideas '.  But 
neither  he  nor  any  of  his  many  followers  has  ever  been  able 
to  devise  a  tenable  formula  to  express  the  (unthinkable)  rela- 
tion of  the  plastic  '  Ideasjj^e-use  to  the  immutable  '  Ideas  ' 
they  have  vainly  po^tuTated.  Hence  though  we  may  be  glad 
that  he  has  expressed  for  all  time  the  perfect  exemplar  of  the 
rationalistic  temper,  we  cannot  in  these  days  imitate  his 
superb  fidelity  to  an  impracticable  ideal.  The  growth  of 
Science  and  the  application  of  Knowledge  to  Life  are  too 
stupendous  facts  to  be  ignored  even  in  the  seclusion  of 
academic  lecture-rooms.  And  so,  though  philosophers  as  a 
body  will  naturally  be  the  last  persons  to  admit  it,  it  must 
eventually  be  recognized  that  Protagoras's  vision  of  a  Truth 
that  did  not  shun  commerce  with  man  was  truer  than  Plato's 
dream  of  an  Eternal  Order  that  transcends  all  human  un- 
derstanding. 


30 


NOTE. 

Since  the  above  study  was  written  my  attention  has  been 
called  to  an  article  on  Plato  and  Protagoras  in  the  Philosophi- 
cal Review,  xvi.,  469,  (September,  1907)  by  Prof.  J.  Watson. 
Its  appearance  is  a  welcome  sign  of  the  times  in  so  far  as 
it  indicates  a  perception  that  the  old  controversy  between 
Protagoras  and  Plato  is  by  no  means  dead  and  recognizes  that 
it  turns  on  essentially  the  same  point  as  the  modern  issue  be- 
tween Humanism  and  Absolutism.  But  Prof.  Watson  could 
have  very  materially  enhanced  the  timeliness  and  relevance 
of  his  discussion  by  taking  more  adequate  cognizance  of  the 
Neo-Protagorean  position.  Even  if  nay  Studies  in  Humanism 
(pp.  33-38,  145-46,  and  298-347)  appeared  too  recently  to  be 
used  by  him,  he  might  at  least  have  referred  to  a  quite  ex- 
plicit article  which  appeared  in  the  Quarterly  Review  so  long 
ago  as  January,  1906.  Instead  of  this  he  confines  his  polemic 
to  a  passing  remark  in  the  Preface  of  my  Humanism,  the 
full  justification  of  which  is  only  forthcoming  in  the  present 
study.  It  is,  however,  satisfactory  to  find  that  he  also  thinks 
that  Plato  meant  to  give  the  veritable  views  of  Protagoras. 
He  holds  also  that  Plato,  when  writing  the  Thecetetus,  had 
access  to  the  treatise  of  Protagoras,  a  position  which  I  have 
given  reasons  for  thinking  not  only  intrinsically  improbable, 
in  view  of  the  apologetic  tone  of  the  Platonic  reproductions, 
but  also  untenable,  as  ignoring  the  external  authority  of 
Diogenes  Laertius,  ix.,  52.  So  despite  of  what  I  said  in 
Studies  in  Humanism,  p.  37,  it  now  seems  to  me  far  more 
likely  that  Plato  was  relying  wholly  on  oral  tradition  about  a 
work  that  was  no  longer  extant.  The  Speech  Prof.  Watson 
ascribes  to  a  '  developed '  Protagoreanism  fabricated  by  Plato 


31 

himself,  without  attempting  to  explain  why  Plato  should 
proceed  to  '  develop '  a  doctrine  for  which  he  had  not  yet 
stated  the  authentic  grounds,  and  then  return  to  the  unde- 
veloped form  without  refuting  its  '  developments  '.  He  says 
nothing  about  the  relevance  of  the  discussion  of  Error,  and 
particularly  of  190  E,  to  the  issue,  and  his  whole  exposition 
of  Plato's  arguments  is  unfortunately  far  too  general  and 
goes  too  little  into  the  detail  of  the  text  to  establish  any  of. 
his  contentions. 


THE   ABERDEEN  UNIVERSITY   PRESS    LIMITED- 


RETURN TO: 


CIRCULATION  DEPARTMENT 
198  Main  Stacks 


LOAN  PERIOD     1 
Home  Use 

2 

3 

4 

5 

6 

ALL  BOOKS  MAY  BE  RECALLED  AFTER  7  DAYS. 

Renewals  and  Recharges  may  be  made  4  days  prior  to  the  due  date. 
Books  may  be  renewed  by  calling  642-3405. 


DUE  AS  STAMPED  BELOW. 

npCi 

6  2001 

V    CLUUT 

MAR  2  8  2005 

FORM  NO.  DD6                        UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA,  BERKELEY 
50M    4-04                                                  Berkeley,  California  94720-6000