Skip to main content

Full text of "Political free trade : the Lectures on jurisprudence and the Wealth of nations"

See other formats


UNIVERSITY  OF 

ILLINOIS  LIBRARY 

AT  URBANA-CHAMPAIGN 

BOOKSTACKS 


be  charged  a  minim, fed£bel°w.  You  may 


JAN  04  2000 


AfOt/  j  § 


7999 


When  renewing  hv  ~| 

b*«  w»i«»"d^  2,ve' wri,e  new  *■«  *«. 

L162 


STX 


BEBR 

FACULTY  WORKING 
PAPER  NO.  89-1537 


Political  Free  Trade?: 

The  Lectures  on  Jurisprudence 

and  the  Wealth  of  Nations 


Salim  Rashid 


College  of  Commerce  and  Business  Administration 
Bureau  of  Economic  and  Business  Research 
University  of  Illinois  Urbana-Champaign 


Digitized  by  the  Internet  Archive 

in  2011  with  funding  from 

University  of  Illinois  Urbana-Champaign 


http://www.archive.org/details/politicalfreetra1537rash 


BEBR 


FACULTY  WORKING  PAPER  NO.  89-1537 

College  of  Commerce  and  Business  Administration 

University  of  Illinois  at  Urbana- Champaign 

February  1989 


Political  Free  Trade?:   The  Lectures  on  Jurisprudence 
and  the  Wealth  of  Nations 

Salim  Rashid,  Professor 
Department  of  Economics 


ABSTRACT 

The  arguments  for  Free-Trade  presented  in  the  earlier  Lectures  do 
not  coincide  with  those  provided  in  the  Wealth  of  Nations.   It  is 
argued  that  these  differences  may  tell  us  about  the  possible  influence 
of  the  Physiocrats  as  well  as  Adam  Smith's  political  leanings. 


POLITICAL  FREE  TRADE?:   THE  LECTURES  ON  JURISPRUDENCE 
AND  THE  WEALTH  OF  NATIONS 

That  the  argument  for  Free  Trade  in  the  Lectures  on  Jurisprudence 
differs  in  significant  ways  from  that  in  the  Wealth  of  Nations  is  a 
point  that  appears  to  have  escaped  notice  so  far.   Two  different  argu- 
ments for  Free  Trade  are  given  in  the  Lectures  and  neither  of  them  is 
quite  the  argument  later  provided  in  the  Wealth  of  Nations.   In  view 
of  the  importance  of  Free  Trade  both  In  the  history  of  economics  as 
well  as  in  Adam  Smith's  own  conceptual  scheme  it  is  worth  examining 
this  difference  more  closely.   After  describing  the  axiomatic  basis 
for  Free-Trade,  as  developed  primarily  in  Book.  IV  of  the  Wealth  of 
Nations ,  in  the  rest  of  the  Introduction,  section  II  goes  on  to  quote 
from  the  Lectures  on  Jurisprudence  to  illustrate  how  the  argument 
there  differs  from  that  in  the  Wealth  of  Nations.   Section  III  con- 
siders the  possible  significance  of  the  change  in  argument,  which 
moves  us  away  from  the  utilitarian  framework  of  the  "Mercantilist" 
literature  towards  the  economic  aspects  of  the  natural-law  tradition 
of  moral  philosophers,  while  Section  IV  considers  how  the  change  in 
argument  may  have  Influenced  the  perception  of  Smith  as  a 
"politician."  The  argument  in  the  Wealth  of  Nations,  it  will  be  re- 
called, is  based  on  three  axioms. 

Al.   Individuals  wish  to  maximize  wealth. 

A2.   Individuals  know  better  than  governments  how  to  maximize 
their  own  wealth. 

A3.   National  wealth  is  the  sum  of  individual  wealth. 
Al  and  A2  establish  that  a  policy  of  non-interference  will  make  indi- 
viduals richest,  while  A3  makes  this  policy  socially  optimal  also.   So 


-2- 


far,  the  axioms  establish  that  leaving  a  people  free  to  trade  is  the 

best  way  to  enrich  them.   To  apply  it  to  international  trade,  we  need 

to  add 

A4.   In  international  affairs,  nations  are  to  be  treated  as 
individuals. 

By  means  of  A4  a  conclusion  which  had  been  widely  accepted  for 

domestic  trade  was  projected  into  international  trade.   The  reader 

will  recall  how  something  very  much  like  A4  is  to  be  found  in  Dudley 

3 
North's  Discourse  on  Trade,   and  one  is  tempted  to  think  of  the  influ- 
ence of  Hugo  Grotius,  Samuel  Pufendorf  and  the  school  of  distinguished 
seventeenth  century  theorists  of  international  law.   Francis  Hutcheson 
was  the  most  prominent  teacher  of  these  doctrines  in  Britain  and  Smith 
no  doubt  imbibed  a  great  deal  from  them.   Nonetheless,  the  case  for 
free  trade  in  the  Lectures  is  not  unfolded  in  axiomatic  fashion,  and 
does  not  reflect  these  moral  philosophers. 

Before  turning  to  the  economic  arguments  of  the  Lectures ,  it  may 
be  useful  to  provide  some  illustrations  of  the  earlier  use  of  personal 
relations  in  giving  a  basis  for  international  relations.   The  follow- 
ing are  taken  from  the  systematic  and  scholarly  exposition  of  Richard 
Zouche  (1650)4 

To  community  in  time  of  peace  belongs  also  owner- 
ship... and  such  ownership,  in  movable  goods,  is 
acquired  generally  by  the  same  modes  as  among  pri- 
vate persons. 

There  is  due  between  different  princes  or  peoples  a 
right  of  civil  convention,  by  virtue  of  which  they 
bind  themselves ,  as  do  private  persons. 

As  lawsuits  arise  from  wrongs  and  injuries  between 
private  persons,  so  wars  arise  between  those 
[peoples]  who  have  no  judge.   [emphasis  added] 


-3- 

II.  There  are  actually  two  different  arguments  for  free  trade  in  the 
Lectures.  The  first  one  develops  the  therae  that  wealth  and  abundance 
are  the  same  and  things  that  are  abundant  must  be  cheap.   In  the 

quotes  that  follow  from  the  Lectures  it  is  important  to  note  that 
"natural  price"  as  used  by  Smith  has  no  necessary  relationship  with 

natural-law  and  is  simply  Smith's  way  of  describing  the  remuneration 

necessary  to  attract  and  keep  someone  at  any  given  job. 

Whatever  policy  tends  to  raise  the  market  price 
above  the  naturall  one  diminishes  publick  opulence 
and  naturall  wealth  of  the  state.   For  dearness  and 
scarcity,  abundance  and  cheapness,  are  we  may  say 
synoniraous  terras.   For  whatever  abounds  much  will  be 
sold  to  the  inferior  people,  whereas  what  is  scarce 
will  be  sold  to  those  only  of  superior  fortune,  and 
the  quantity  will  consequently  be  small.   So  far 
therefore  as  any  thing  is  a  convenience  or  necessary 
of  life  and  tends  to  the  happiness  of  mankind,  so 
far  is  the  dearness  detrimentall  as  it  confines  the 
necessary  to  a  few  and  diminishes  the  happiness  of 
the  inferior  sort.   Whatever  therefore  raises  or 
keeps  up  the  price  of  them  diminishes  the  opulence 
and  happiness  and  ease  of  the  country. 

On  the  basis  of  this  argument,  monopolies,  which  raise  market  price 

above  natural  price,  are  seen  to  be  detrimental  to  economic  welfare. 

The  market  price  can  also  be  below  the  natural  price  due  to  a 

bounty.   In  this  case,  more  workers  are  attracted  into  the  favored 

industry.   Since  this  influx  of  workers  means  a  loss  of  workers  from 

other  industries — an  implicit  use  of  "full  employment"  and  explicit 

use  of  the  wages-fund  model — the  value  of  aggregate  produce  is  said  to 

be  lower.   This  part  of  the  argument  is  developed  more  through  example 

than  through  a  chain  of  reasoning. 

The  price  of  grass  being  raised,  butcher's  meat, 
in  consequence  of  its  dependence  upon  it,  must  be 
raised  also.   So  that  if  the  price  of  corn  is  dimin- 
ished, the  price  of  other  commodities  is  necessarily 


-4- 


raised.   The  price  of  corn  has  indeed  fallen  from  42 
to  35,  but  the  price  of  hay  has  risen  from  25  to  near 
50  shillings.   As  the  price  of  hay  has  risen,  horses 
are  not  so  easily  kept,  and  therefore  the  price  of 
carriage  has  risen  also.   But  whatever  encreases  the 
price  of  carriage  diminishes  plenty  in  the  market. 
Upon  the  whole,  therefore,  it  is  by  far  the  best 
police  to  leave  things  to  their  natural  course,  and 
allow  no  bounties,  nor  impose  taxes  on  commodities. 

The  second  argument  starts  with  the  premise  that  all  voluntary 

exchange  is  mutually  advantageous.   It  is  embedded  within  a  detailed 

attack  on  the  principle  that  opulence  consists  of  money. 

The  bad  idea  of  publick  opulence  consisting  in 
money  has  been  productive  of  other  bad  effects. 
Upon  this  principle  most  pernicious  relations  have 
been  established.   These  species  of  commerce  which 
drain  us  of  our  money  are  thought  dissadvantageous 
and  these  which  increase  it  beneficial;  therefore 
the  former  are  prohibited  and  the  latter  encour- 
aged. 

All  commerce  that  is  carried  on  betwixt  any  two 
countries  must  necessarily  be  advantageous  to  both. 
The  very  intention  of  commerce  is  to  exchange  your 
own  commodities  for  others  which  you  think  will  be 
more  convenient  for  you.   When  two  men  trade  be- 
tween themselves  it  is  undoubtedly  for  the  advan- 
tage of  both.  The  one  has  perhaps  more  of  one 
species  of  commodities  than  he  has  occasion  for,  he 
therefore  exchanges  a  certain  quantity  of  it  with 
the  other,  for  another  commodity  that  will  be  more 
useful  to  him.   The  other  agrees  to  the  bargain  on 
the  same  account,  and  in  this  manner  the  mutual  com- 
merce is  advantageous  to  both.   The  case  is  exactly 
the  same  betwixt  any  two  nations.   [emphasis  added] 

After  this  explicit  identification  of  the  principles  guiding  two- 
person  and  two-nation  trade  there  follows  an  argument  that,  since  rich 
men  gain  more  than  poor  men  when  they  trade,  rich  nations  will  gain 

Q 

more  than  poor  nations  when  they  trade. 

In  general  we  may  observe  that  these  jealousies  and 
prohibitions  are  most  hurtfull  to  the  richest 
nations,  and  that  in  proportion  as  a  free  commerce 


-5- 


would  be  advantageous.   When  a  rich  man  and  a  poor 
man  deal  with  one  another,  both  of  them  will  in- 
crease their  riches,  if  they  deal  prudently,  but 
the  rich  man's  stock  will  increase  in  a  greater 
proportion  than  the  poor  man's.   In  like  manner, 
when  a  rich  and  a  poor  nation  engage  in  trade  the 
rich  nation  will  have  the  greatest  advantage,  and 
therefore  the  prohibition  of  this  commerce  is  most 
hurtful  to  it  of  the  two.   All  our  trade  with 
France  is  prohibited  by  the  high  duties  imposed  on 
every  French  commodity  imported.   It  would  however 
have  been  better  police  to  encourage  our  trade 
with  France.   [emphasis  added] 

After  some  further  description  of  the  silliness  of  the  system  which 

9 
identifies  money  and  wealth,  Smith  concludes: 

From  the  above  considerations  it  appears  that 
Brittain  should  by  all  means  be  made  a  free  port, 
that  there  should  be  no  interruptions  of  any  kind 
made  to  forreign  trade,  that  if  it  were  possible 
to  defray  the  expences  of  government  by  any  other 
method,  all  duties,  customs,  and  excise  should  be 
abolished,  and  that  free  commerce  and  liberty  of 
exchange  should  be  allowed  with  all  nations  and 
for  all  things. 

The  first  argument  provided  in  the  lectures  has  a  modern  ring  in 
that  a  demand-supply  framework  is  (implicitly)  used  to  evaluate  the 
costs  of  economic  policy;  the  second  argument,  on  the  other  hand,  has 
a  definite  axiomatic  ring  to  it — all  free  exchange  is  mutually 
beneficial — but  it  does  not  quite  tell  us  how  to  make  the  transition 
to  the  growth  of  national  wealth.   The  first  argument  may  be  con- 
sidered a  "cost-benefit"  or  utilitarian  approach,  while  the  second  one, 
although  noticing  the  benefits  of  freedom,  flows  more  easily  from  a 
natural  rights  framework.   Before  proceeding  to  discuss  the  possible 
implications  of  the  change  in  argument,  it  is  worth  noting  Keynes' 
view  that  there  was  a  general  presumption  that  the  two  methods  would 
lead  to  the  same  conclusion. 


-6- 


Suppose  that  by  the  workings  of  natural  laws  indi- 
viduals pursuring  their  own  interests  with 
enlightenment  in  conditions  of  freedom  always  tend 
to  promote  the  general  interest  at  the  same  time! 
To  the  philosophical  doctrine  that  government  has 
no  right  to  interfere,  and  the  divine  that  it  has 
not  need  to  interfere,  there  is  added  a  scientific 
proof  that  its  interference  is  inexpedient.   This 
is  the  third  current  of  thought,  just  discoverable 
in  Adam  Smith  who  was  already  in  the  main  to  allow 
the  public  good  to  rest  on  "the  natural  effort  of 
every  individual  to  better  his  own  condition,"  but 
not  fully  and  self-consciously  developed  until  the 
nineteenth  century  begins.   The  principle  of 
laissez-faire  had  arrived  to  harmonise  individual- 
ism and  socialism,  and  to  make  at  one  Hume's  egoism 
with  the  greatest  good  of  the  greatest  number. 

Nonetheless,  the  potential  for  a  conflict  was  clearly  stated  by 
11 


Bentham. 


I  have  not  .  .  .  any  horror,  sentimental  or 
anarchical,  of  the  hand  of  government.   1  leave  it 
to  Adam  Smith,  and  the  champions  of  the  rights  of 
man  (for  confusion  of  ideas  will  jumble  together 
the  best  subjects  and  the  worst  citizens  upon  the 
same  ground)  to  talk  of  invasions  of  natural 
liberty,  and  to  give  as  a  special  argument  against 
this  or  that  law,  an  argument  the  effect  of  which 
would  be  to  put  a  negative  upon  all  the  laws. 


-7- 

III.   Why  did  Smith  change  the  nature  of  the  arguments  for  free  trade 
in  the  period  between  the  Lectures  and  the  Wealth  of  Nations?   Let  us 
first  note  the  internal  weakness  of  the  argument  based  on  differences 
in  market  and  natural  price.   The  link  between  cheapness  and  abundance 
is  flawless  and  the  argument  against  having  market  prices  higher  than 
natural  prices  a  valid  conclusion  therefrom.   However,  the  claim  that 
bounties  actually  hurt  is  not  clearly  developed.   Instead  of  focussing 
upon  the  inefficiency  of  taxing  people  to  pay  for  the  bounty,  Smith 
goes  on  to  talk  about  grass  and  fodder  and  so  on.   The  inconclusive- 
ness  of  the  argument  probably  struck  him  during  the  composition  of  the 
Wealth  of  Nations.   Secondly;  it  should  be  noted  that  the  utilitarian 
approach  to  free  trade  did  not  entirely  disappear  from  the  Wealth  of 
Nations.   The  analysis  of  scarcities  in  Book  IV  provides  a  curious 

example  where  a  conclusion  as  strong  as  that  of  a  natural  rights  argu- 

12 
raent  is  drawn  from  a  "cost  benefit"  analysis.    Thirdly,  it  has  been 

noted  that  Smith's  price  theory  in  the  Lectures ,  but  not  in  the  Wealth 

13 
of  Nations,  is  based  upon  labor  as  the  only  cost  of  production. 

Could  the  move  to  incorporate  non-labor  costs  have  convinced  Smith 
that  the  contrast  between  market  price  and  natural  price  was  in- 
adequate for  his  purposes?  By  rejecting  an  argument  based  on  prices 
and  taking  up  one  based  on  the  benefits  of  freedom,  Smith  is  moving 
towards  the  Pufendorf-Hutcheson  legacy  over  time.    As  the  cost- 
benefit  approach  can  lead  to  a  defense  of  intervention — witness 
Bentham's  Defense  of  a  Maximum — there  is  the  possibility  that  Smith 
wished  to  minimize  any  exceptions  to  free  trade. 


-8- 

If  it  is  indeed  true  that  Smith  altered  one  of  his  main  arguments 

against  government  interference  between  the  Lectures  and  the  Wealth  of 

Nations ,  could  the  change  have  had  something  to  do  with  the  Physiocrats? 

This  is  a  connection  that  has  been  raised  and  dismissed  often.   In 

past  discussions  of  Physiocratic  influence,  such  as  that  of  Edwin 

Cannan,  most  attention  has  been  drawn  to  the  insertion  of  a  theory  of 

distribution  in  the  Wealth  of  Nations.   Perhaps  this  is  due  to  Dugald 

Stewart's  claim,  in  his  Account  of  Smith's  life,  that  Smith  was  in 

possession  of  his  principal  free-trade  results  by  1755.   However,  in 

the  quote  accompanying  this   claim,  there  are  only  results,  such  as 

the  beneficience  of  free  trade,  but  no  proofs. 

Little  else  is  required  to  carry  a  state  to  the 
highest  degree  of  affluence  from  the  lowest 
barbarism  but  peace,  easy  taxes,  and  a  tolerable 
administration  of  justice;  all  the  rest  being 
brought  about  by  the  natural  course  of  things.   All 
governments  which  thwart  this  natural  course,  which 
force  things  into  another  channel,  or  which  en- 
deavour to  arrest  the  progress  of  society  at  a 
particular  point,  are  unnatural,  and,  to  support 
themselves,  are  obliged  to  be  oppressive  and 
tyrannical  .  .  . 

Smith's  membership  in  a  society  which  awarded  premiums,  the  Edinburgh 

Society,  provides  some  circumstantial  grounds  for  believing  that  Smith 

was  not  quite  seen  as  an  ardent  supporter  of  "Free-Trade"  until  after 

his  professorial  days.   The  prevailing  contrary  impression  is  probably 

due  to  John  Rae's  claim  that 

In  his  [Smith's]  lectures  on  jurisprudence  and 
politics  he  had  taught  the  doctrine  of  free  trade 
from  the  first,  and  not  the  least  remarkable  result 
of  his  thirteen  years  work  in  Glasgow  was  that 
before  he  left  he  had  practically  converted  that 
city  to  his  views 


-9- 

A  careful  consideration  of  the  self-interest  of  the  (protected)  trade 
of  Glasgow  merchants  would  lead  us  to  think  otherwise.   While  this 

claim  of  Rae's  has  been  repeated  by  various  scholars,  Rae  himself 

1  f\ 
contradicts  it  30  pages  later. 

those  Glasgow  merchants  .  .  .  are  not  necessarily 
free-traders  because  they  want  free  import  of  raw 
materials.   That  was  advocated  as  strongly  from  the 
old  mercantilist  standpoint  as  it  is  now  from  the 
free-trade  one. 

How  are  we  to  tell  whether  Smith  was  able  to  justify  his  conclusion  in 
the  quote  provided  by  Dugald  Stewart?   The  existence  of  a  different 
argument  in  the  Lectures  suggests  that  Smith  may  have  begun  from  a 
natural  rights  basis  in  the  1750s,  abandoned  it  for  about  a  decade, 
and  then  returned  to  it  again.   Whether  or  not  the  return  was  stimu- 
lated by  the  Physiocrats  we  do  not  know.  When  Stewart  first  discussed 
Smith's  priority  on  this  issue,  in  1793,  he  was  convinced  of  Smith's 
independent  discovery  of  free  trade.   The  Lectures  on  Political 
Economy,  delivered  by  Stewart  between  1798  and  1810,  are  not  as  clear 
on  this  point  and  in  these  lectures  Stewart  even  suggests  that  Smith 
was  a  popular  version  of  Physiocratic  ideas.   There  have  been  similar 
"underground"  comments  on  the  Physiocrat-Smith  connection  in  the 
literature,  but  few  detailed  arguments.  Mogens  Boserup  writes,  in  his 
book  of  readings,  that  he  has  chosen  extracts  from  Smith  in  order  to 
illustrate  the  fact  that  Smith  "may  be  understood  as  a  successor  of 
the  Physiocratic  school."  Hans  Breras  makes  a  more  pointed  remark, 
"Much  of  what  Smith  had  to  say  had  been  said  before — but  in  French. 
Academic  etiquette  of  his  day  demanded  no  acknowledgements,  and  he 
offered  none."  In  view  of  the  fact  that  the  early  perception  of  Smith 


-10- 


in  Germany  was  as  a  Physiocrat,  this  is  perhaps  an  issue  worth 

*j    ,  •    17 
reconsideration. 


-11- 

IV.   The  attraction  of  the  approach  eventually  adopted  in  the  Wealth 
of  Nations  is  its  close  link  with  natural  rights  arguments  and  politi- 
cal radicalism.   The  fact  that  Smith  had  placed  human  labor  as  the 
primary  agent  for  creating  wealth  no  doubt  helped  this  link.   Smith's 
sympathy  for  laborers  and  farm  workers  and  his  hostility  towards 
masters  and  landlords  has  long  been  noted.   Combined  with  the  general 
emphasis  on  liberty  (one  recalls  the  radical  stress  on  liberty  given 
by  his  old  teacher,  Hutcheson) ,  the  ideas  would  appear  as  a  powerful 

dissolvent  of  traditional  ideas,  especially  in  Europe,  a  fact  appre- 

18 
ciated  by  such  commentators  as  Charles  Ganilh  and  Adolphe  Blanqui 

Wealth,  produced  by  labour — restores  man  to  his 
primitive  dignity,  through  the  sentiment  of  his 
independence,  through  his  obedience  to  laws  common 
to  all,  and  his  sharing  in  the  benefits  of  society 
in  proportion  to  his  services  (Ganilh) 

there  were  no  longer  any  sterile  occupations,  since 
every  body  was  capable  of  giving  things  an  exchange 
value,  by  means  of  labor.  What  an  encouragement  to 
men  ill-favored  by  fortune  and  to  those  who  did  not 
expect  the  boon  of  an  inheritance!  (Blanqui) 

It  is  a  noticeable  feature  of  Smith's  analysis  that  he  takes  the 

possibility  of  harmful  effects  due  to  a  violation  of  natural  rights  to 

be  sufficient  grounds  for  believing  that  harm  actually  does  occur. 

The  Laws  of  Settlement  are  a  case  in  point. 

The  link  between  natural-rights  economics  and  political  radicalism 

would  have  been  evident  to  contemporaries  and  it  perhaps  explains  the 

fact  that  the  first  Parliamentary  reference  to  the  Wealth  of  Nations 

was  made  by  someone  ignorant  of  economics,  by  Charles  James  Fox,  a 

19 
reference  that  helped  to  bolster  sales  considerably.     Subsequently, 

we  find  some  early  favorable  references  to  Smith  in  William  Godwin  and 


-12- 

Tom  Paine,  while  one  of  Smith's  earliest  admiring  editors,  Jeremiah 
Joyce,  also  provides  evidence  of  being  a  political  radical  by  his 
sharp  criticism  of  that  instrument  of  tyranny — the  national  debt. 
Another  admirer  of  Adam  Smith,  Thomas  Archard,  wrote  a  pamphlet 
defending  the  suppression  of  the  French  Nobility.  Lord  Lauderdale, 
later  a  sharp  critic,  was  a  radical  in  his  youth,  when  he  is  said  to 
have  "worshipped"  Smith.   The  point  is  further  strengthened  by  Lord 
Cockburn's  comment  that  Smith's  death  was  ignored  by  all  except  the 
political  youth  of  Scotland.   In  1793  the  Marquis  of  Lansdowne  even 
went  so  far  as  to  claim  that  the  ideas  of  the  French  Revolution  were 
not  new  but  had  in  fact  been  propounded  earlier  by  such  respectable 
British  authors  as  Adam  Smith  and  Dean  Tucker.   Dugald  Stewart  stated 
that  people  who  once  associated  with  Adam  Smith,  felt  embarrassed 
about  any  association  with  "liberal"  principles  in  the  wake  of  the 

French  Revolution.   John  Rae  has  provided  a  perceptive  statement  of 

20 
the  political  impact  of  Free  Trade  ideas  in  the  1790s. 

By  French  principles  the  public  understood,  it  is 
true,  much  more  than  the  abolition  of  all  commercial 
and  agrarian  privilege  which  was  advocated  by  Smith, 
but  in  their  recoil  they  made  no  fine  distinctions, 
and  they  naturally  felt  their  prejudices  strongly 
confirmed  when  they  found  men  like  the  Marquis  of 
Lansdowne,  who  were  believers  in  the  so-called 
French  principles  and  believers  at  the  same  time 
in  the  principles  of  Adam  Smith,  declaring  that  the 
two  things  were  substantially  the  same. 

Nor  should  this  entirely  surprise  us.   That  Adam  Smith  had  a  par- 
tiality for  radicalism  is  evidenced  by  his  admiration  for  both 

21 
Rousseau  and  Voltaire, 


-13- 


Voltaire  set  himself  to  correct  the  vices  and 
follies  of  mankind  by  laughing  at  them,  and  some- 
times by  treating  them  with  severity,  but  Rousseau 
conducts  the  reader  to  reason  and  truth  by  the 
attractions  of  sentiment  and  the  force  of  convic- 
tion.  His  "Social  Compact"  will  one  day  avenge 
all  the  persecutions  he  suffered. 

Janes  Seattle  criticized  David  Hume's  skepticism  in  his  Essay  on  Truth 

and  later  wrote  to  Lady  Wortley  Montagu  that  even  though  he  had  known 

Smith  well  once,  after  the  publication  of  the  Essay  on  Truth — "nous 

22 

avons  changez  tout  cela."" 

The  early  supporters  of  Free  Trade  in  English  economic  thought 
were  almost  certainly  motivated  by  political  considerations — in  that 
free  trade  with  France,  the  traditional  enemy,  was  a  part  of  the  Tory 
agenda.   With  the  rise  of  Sir  Robert  Walpole,  however,  the  Whigs  began 
to  cautiously  adopt  the  same  "Tory"  attitudes  towards  trade  with 
France.   Philosophically  speaking,  the  attitudes  of  the  natural  rights 
school  were  far  more  consonant  with  the  writers  of  Cato's  Letters  or 
the  Commonweal thmen  surrounding  Lord  Molesworth.   The  attitudes  that 
encouraged  the  philosophy  of  laissez-faire  had  considerable  roots  in 
liberal  religious  and  political  thought,  as  noted  by  Jacob  Viner  and 
M.  L.  Myers."   Ashley's  influential  view  that  Smith's  contribution  lay 
in  making  a  Tory  doctrine,  Free  Trade,  acceptable  to  Whigs  is  liable 
to  misinterpretation  unless  one  recognizes  that  the  underlying  reasons 
for  the  same  policy  had  changed  considerably.   It  is  no  accident  that 

both  John  Locke  and,  a  half  century  later,  Bishop  Law,  embody  the  same 

24 
complex  of  political  and  theological  notions.    When  Francis  Horner 

refused  to  make  public  his  criticisms  of  the  Wealth  of  Nations  because 

the  good  effects  of  that  book  were  yet  to  be  spread  further  he  may 


•14- 


well,  as  a  staunchly  liberal  Whig,  have  had  the  politico-economic 

impact  in  mind.   The  attitude  is  more  explicit  in  John  Stuart  Mill's 

?5 
stated  reason  for  adhering  to  laissez-faire  in  1833.*" 

In  the  meantime  that  principle,  like  other  negative 
ones,  has  work  to  do  yet,  work  mainly  of  a  destroy- 
ing kind,  and  I  am  glad  to  think  it  has  strength 
enough  to  finish  that  after  which  it  must  soon 
expire;  peace  be  with  its  ashes  when  it  does  expire, 
for  I  doubt  much-  if  it  will  reach  the  resurrection. 

Insofar  as  the  movement  towards  a  philosophic  basis  for  free  trade  had 
socio-political  origins,  Smith  supports  the  thesis  of  Leo  Rogin  that 

"new  systems  first  emerge  in  the  guise  of  arguments  in  the  context  of 

j    i    c    m26 
social  reform. 

Finally,  it  is  worth  reiterating  that  Smith  is  by  no  means  so 

strongly  a  free  trader  in  his  Lectures ,  as  in  the  Wealth  of  Nations. 

Emphasis  does  a  lot  in  an  argument,  and  the  emphasis  on  free  trade  in 

the  Lectures ,  relative  to  all  the  other  matter  there,  even  within  the 

economic  sections  alone,  is  not  as  strong  as  it  subsequently  became  in 

the  Wealth  of  Nations.   If  we  add  to  this  the  fact,  already  noted  by 

the  editors  of  the  Lectures ,  that  the  Lectures  take  a  more  positive 

view  of  government,  as  well  as  the  fact  that  the  Lectures  accept  some 

common  beliefs,  such  as  the  backward  bending  supply  curve  of  labor  and 

the  validity  of  "balance-of-employment"  arguments,  it  would  appear 

that  Smith's  classroom  lectures  were  not  as  revolutionary  when  deliv- 

27 
ered  as  they  appeared  to  be  with  hindsight.    Smith's  friends  were 

not  engaging  in  repetitious  praise  when  they  greeted  the  Wealth  of 

Nations  as  a  system,  as  though  this  were  an  aspect  of  Smith  hitherto 

28 
undeveloped.    They  knew  well  a  professor  of  philosophical  history, 


-15- 


whose  economic  interpretations  gave  them  considerable  pride,  but  the 

99 
author  of  an  axiomatic  basis  for  free-trade  was  a  revelation." 


-16- 

Notes 

W.  Mitchell,  Types  of  Economic  Theory  (New  York  1967),  I,  60-64. 
This  interpretation  is  repeated  by  several  authors,  e.g.,  A.  K. 
Chaudhuri,  The  Wealth  of  Nations  (Calcutta:   World  Press,  1967).   Some 
early  critics  noted  clearly  the  nature  of  Smith's  axioms,  e.g.,  W.  J. 
Mickle  in  his  Introduction  to  the  Lusiad,  as  described  by  Jacob  Viner 
in  his  Introduction  to  John  Rae,  Life  of  Adam  Smith  (New  York:   Kelley, 
1965),  73. 

2 
I  have  not  been  able  to  find  the  explicit  use  of  A4  (below)  in  the 

literature.   Its  effect  depends  upon  an  ambiguity  between  the  wealth 

of  all  nations  and  that  of  individual  nations.   "International  law  Is 

on  the  whole  an  analogical  extension  of  the  laws  of  justice,  much  as 

in  Grotius,"  writes  Knud  Haakanssen,  "What  Might  Properly  Be  Called 

Natural  Jurisprudence,"  in  The  Origins  and  Nature  of  the  Scottish 

Enlightenment,  ed.  R.  H.  Campbell  and  A.  S.  Skinner  (John  Donald, 

Edinburgh,  1982),  208. 

3 
Dudley  North,  Discourses  upon  Trade  (London:   1691),  reprinted 

(1971)  by  Johnson  Reprint  Corporation.   The  Preface  claims  to  quote 

North  on  this  point  and  North  himself  expresses  such  sentiments  on 

p.  14. 

4 
R.  Zouche,  An  Exposition  ...  of  Law  between  Nations  trans.  J.  L. 

Brierly  (Baltimore:   Lord  Baltimore  Press,  1911),  8,  23,  27.   For 

Pufendorf,  see  De  Officio  Hominis. . . (New  York:   Oxford  University 

Press,  1927),  108. 

Lectures  on  Jurisprudence  ed.  R.  L.  Meek,  D.  D.  Raphael  and  P.  G. 
Stein  (Oxford:   0.  U.  P.  1978),  362.   As  I  have  been  unable  to  detect 
any  significant  differences  between  the  two  extant  accounts  of  the 
Lectures ,  I  have  used  them  interchangably. 

There  is  no  matter  directly  bearing  on  my  topic  in  R.  F. 
Teichgraber,  Free  Trade  and  Moral  Philosophy  (Durham:   Duke  U.  P., 
1986),  or  in  Donald  Winch,  Adam  Smith's  Politics  (Cambridge,  1983), 
even  though  we  are  all  agreed  on  giving  Smith's  political  views 
greater  prominence. 


6rt 

Op. 

cit. , 

499. 

7„ 

Op. 

cit. , 

511. 

80p. 

cit.  , 

512. 

9^ 
Op. 

cit. , 

514. 

As  quoted  by  R.  Kanth,  Political  Economy  and  Laissez  Faire  (New 
Jersey  1986),  25.   This  book  provides  a  welcome  change  In  its  reasser- 
tion  of  the  politics  in  Political  Economy. 


-17- 

W.  Stark,  ed.   Jeremy  Bentham's  Economic  Writings  (London  1954), 
vol.  3,  257-58. 

12 

Smith's  arguments  were  applied,  with  some  vehemence,  by  Edmund 

Burke,  Thoughts  and  Details  on  the  Scarcity  (London  179  5). 

The  tension  between  the  "natural  law"  and  the  "utilitarian"  argu- 
ments continued  throughout  classical  economics.   Bentham,  for  example, 
first  refined  the  "natural  law"  argument  and  then  the  "utilitarian" 
one,  whereas  J.  S.  Mill  did  the  reverse.  E.  F.  Paul,  Moral  Revolution 
and  Economic  Science  (Greenwood  Press,  1979).   P.  Schwartz,  The  New 
Political  Economy  of  J.  S.  Mill  (Duke  U.P.,  1972). 

13 

M.  Bowley,  Studies  in  the  History  of  Economic  Thought  before  1370 

(London:   MacMillan,  1973),  108,  121. 

14 

That  the  Lectures  clearly  demonstrate  Smith's  philosophical 

sources  is  also  emphasized  in  E.  Pesciarelli,  "On  Adam  Smith's  Lectures 
on  Jurisprudence,"  Scottish  Journal  of  Political  Economy  (Feb.  1986), 
33,  1,  74-85. 

E.  Cannan,  introduction  to  the  Wealth  of  Nations  (New  York, 
1397),  xxxix.   Collected  Works  of  Dugald  Stewart  (Edinburgh  1372),  X, 
68. 

■I  C. 

John  Rae,  Adam  Smith,  op.  cit . ,  119,  60,  92. 

17Collected  Works  of  Dugald  Stewart  (Edinburgh  1858-1873),  VIII, 
306.   M.  Boserup,  Peres  Egne  Ord  (Copenhagen).   H.  Brems,  "Frequently 
Wrong,  but  Rarely  in  Doubt,"  Challenge  (Nov. -Dec,  1987),  55.   I  am 
grateful  to  Hans  Brems  for  the  translation  of  Boserup' s  Danish  original. 
K.  Tribe,  Governing  Economy  (Cambridge  University  Press,  1988),  chs. 
6  and  7 . 

18 

Much  of  the  evidence  on  this  point  has  been  gathered  in  Eli 

Ginzberg,  The  House  of  Adam  Smith  (New  York  1930). 

Charles  Ganilh,  An  Inquiry  into  the  Various  Systems  of  Political 
Economy  (New  York;  Kelley  reprint;  1966),  46. 

Adolphi  Blanqui,  History  of  Political  Economy  in  Europe  (New  York, 
1880),  386. 

19 

John  Rae  wishes  to  minimize  the  impact  of  the  reference  to  the 

Wealth  of  Nations  by  Fox,  but  Homer  Vanderblue  shows  that  Smith's 
publisher  did  take  the  Impact  of  Fox's  favorable  reference  quite 
seriously.   Fox  himself  was  otherwise  ignorant  of  economics.   John 
Rae,  Adam  Smith  (London:   1895),  289.   Homer  Vanderblue,  Adam  Smith 
and  the  Wealth  of  Nations  (Boston,  1936),  5.   "It  was  far  from  refor- 
mers' minds  to  make  government  stronger  and  more  centralized.  Most, 
like  Tom  Paine  and  William  Godwin,  thought  there  was  a  surfeit  of 
government  already  and  aimed  to  fumigate  the  state  of  its  leeches." 
Roy  Porter,  English  Society  in  the  Eighteenth  Century  (London,  1982). 


-18- 

20 

Rae,  op_.  cit. ,  292. 

21 

op.  cit. ,  372.   Smith  is  said  to  have  spoken  of  both  Rousseau 

and  Voltaire  "with  a  kind  of  religious  respect." 

22 

Beattie's  letter  is  in  the  Huntington  Library,  California.   For 

Smith's  continuing  serviceability  to  radical  causes  see  W.  Stafford, 

Socialism,  Radicalism  and  Nostalgia  (Cambridge;  C.U.P.  1987)  and  N.  W. 

Thompson,  The  People's  Science  (Cambridge;  C.U.P. ,  1984).   Michael 

Perelman  has  gathered  together  a  fair  amount  of  evidence  showing  how 

resentful  Smith  was  at  having  to  be  beholden  to  his  social  superiors. 

"Adam  Smith  and  Social  Relations,"  presented  at  the  History  of 

Economics  Society  meetings  (Boston  1987).   He  has  also  noted  Smith's 

radicalism  was  more  petit  bourgeois  than  working-class. 

?3 

W.  J.  Ashley,  "The  Tory  Origin  of  Free  Trade  Policy,"  Quarterly 

Journal  of  Economics  (July  1897).   Ashley's  views  are  repeated  by 

E.  R.  A.  Seligman  in  his  Introduction  to  The  Wealth  of  Nations  (New 

York,  1910).   P.  Langford,  The  Excise  Crisis  (Oxford:   1975);  C. 

Robbins ,  The  Eighteenth  Century  Common  Wealth  Man  (Harvard:   1959); 

M.  L.  Myers,  The  Soul  of  Modern  Economic  Man  (Chicago:   1983); 

J.  Clarke,  English  Society  1660-1832  (Cambridge  1985). 

24 

"By  the  end  of  the  [eighteenth]  century  there  was  often  to  be 

found  the  combination  of  a  thirst  for  knowledge  with  a  critical  and 

realistic  attitude  to  politics  and  religion,"  J.  H.  Plumb,  "Reason  and 

Unreason  in  the  Eighteenth  Century,"  in  Some  Aspects  of  Eighteenth 

Century  England  ed  M.E.  Novak  (UCLA  1971),  15.   It  is  also  of  interest 

to  note  how  some  well-known  industrialists,  such  as  William  Strutt, 

were  strong  radicals.  Margaret  C.  Jacob,  "Scientific  Culture  in  the 

Early  English  Enlightenment:   Mechanisms,  Industry  and  Gentlemanly 

Facts,"  in  A.  C.  Kors  and  P.  Korshin,  eds.,  Anticipations  of  the 

Enlightenment  in  England,  France  and  Germany  (Univ.  of  Penn., 

Philadelphia,  1987),  134-164. 

25 

As  quoted  by  D.  H.,  MacGregor,  Economic  Thought  and  Policy 

(Oxford  1949),  70. 

?6 

L.  Rogin,  The  Meaning  and  Validity  of  Economic  Theory  (London 

1950),  xiii.   This  point  of  view  has  also  been  upheld  by  many  scholars 

in  dealing  with  social  philosophies,  e.g.,  M.  Cowling,  "The  Use  of 

Political  Philosophy  in  Mill,  Green  and  Bentham,"  Historical  Studies, 

5,  (London  1965),  141-152. 

27 

The  treatment  of  Banking  is  the  only  exception  I  can  think  of. 

Perhaps  the  Scottish  banking  problems  of  the  early  1760' s  are  respon- 
sible for  Smith's  caution  on  this  issue. 
Lectures ,  op.  cit. ,  535  and  540. 

28 

R.  H.  Campbell  and  A.  S.  Skinner,  Adam  Smith  (New  York:   St. 

Martins,  1982). 


-19- 

29 

The  example  of  John  Millar  serves  to  strengthen  one  part  and 

weaken  another  part  of  the  thesis  of  this  paper.   Millar's  reaction  to 
the  program  of  free  trade  in  the  Wealth  of  Nations  clearly  shows  that 
he  found  Smith's  espousal  of  this  program  to  be  a  novelty. 

"...  notwithstanding  all  the  pains  he  has  taken,  there  are  many 
of  his  positions  which  1  find  great  difficulty  in  admitting — and  some- 
where 1  am  not  sure  in  what  latitude  he  means  to  establish  them.   In 
particular,  his  great  leading  opinion  concerning  the  unbounded  freedom 
of  trade.   I  have  but  a  vague  notion  how  far  it  is  true,  or  how  far  he 
meant  to  say  it  ought  to  be  carried."   As  quoted  by  T.  Hutchison, 
Before  Adam  Smith  (London,  1988),  412. 

On  the  other  hand,  Millar  himself  was  the  strongest  advocate  of 
liberal  politics  in  the  Scottish  Enlightenment. 


D/432 


HECKMAN       I— 

BINDERY  INC.        |S 

JUN95 

ft-nJ  To-IW    n  MANCHESTER. 
Bom!   lo  no-    ,N01ANA  46962